Skip to main content

Full text of "A handbook of the history of philosophy : for the use of students"

See other formats


BOOK     109.B33    c.  1 

BAX    #    HANDBOOK    OF    HISTORY    OF 

PHILOSOPHY 


3    T153    0D05T7flT    D 


-'«£. 


BOHITS  PHILOSOPHICAL  LIBRARY. 


A  HANDBOOK 


HISTOEY  OF  PHILOSOPHY. 


An^andbook  ,  63 


OF   THE 


EISTOEY   OF   PHILOSOPHY. 


FOB    TEE    USE    OF   STUDENTS, 


BY 


EENEST  BELFORT^BAX. 

EDITOR   OF   '  KAXT's   PROLEGOMENA,'    ETC.: 
CTHOR  OP   '  JEAN   PAUL   MARAT,   A   HI6T0RIC0-EI0GRAPHICAL    SKETCH,'  ETC. 


I, 


ONDON:  GEORaE  BELL  AND  SONS,  YORK  STREET, 
COVENT  GARDEN. 

1S86. 


t^ 


LONDON : 

PKINTED  BY   WILLIAM   CLOWES  AND  feONS,   LIMITED, 

STAMFORD  STEFET   AND  CHAKI^G  CBOSS. 


PREFACE. 


When  I  was  requested  to  undertake  the  editing  and  re- 
^vision  for  Bohn's  Philosophical  Library,  of  a  new  edition 
of  '  Tennemann's  Manual  of  the  History  of  Philosophy,'  a 
"very  brief  examination  sufficed  to  make  it  evident  to  me 
that  the  amount  of  correction  and  alteration  required 
to  bring  the  latter  only  approximately  up  to  date  would 
be  such,  that  the  last  state  of  that  manual  would  bid 
fair  to  resemble  the  condition  of  a  certain  relic  associated 
with  the  Thirty  Years  War,  resj)ecting  which  we  are 
told,  the  "head,  neck,  legs  and  part  of  the  body  have 
been  renewed,  all  the  rest  is  the  real  horse."  It  was 
therefore  decided  that  I  should  undertake  an  entirely 
new  volume  on  the  subject. 

The  plan  adopted  has  been  to  give  a  more  or  less 
detailed  account  of  those  philosophers  who  either  consti- 
tute epochs  in  the  history  of  speculation,  or  at  least  have 
contributed  something  of  their  own  toward  its  subsequent 
development,  without  filling  the  work  unnecessarily  with 
a  mere  crowd  of  names.  Of  course  in  the  case  of  thinkers 
of  subordinate  importance,  a  selection  made  on  this 
principle  must  always  be  open  to  criticism,  but  that  there 
)are  no  flagrant  cases  of  partiality  or  carelessness  is  my 
conscientious  belief. 


VI  PREFACE. 

It  will  be  observed  that  there  is  a  progressive  expansion  ■ 
in  the  treatment  as  modern  times  are  approached.  A 
bibliography  has  been  appended  where  it  has  been  con- 
sidered necessary,  especially  in  the  case  of  those  earlier 
periods  of  which  the  exposition  has  been  more  condensed. 
As  regards  later  \viiters,  the  view  taken  is  that  the 
primary  need  of  the  student  is  to  study  the  original 
works  themselves  rather  than  what  other  people  have 
written  about  them,  desirable  as  this  may  be  as  a 
■  supplementary  aid.  AVorks,  moreover,  treating  of  these 
thinkers  are  numerous,  and  their  titles  readily  accessible 
to  the  student.  I  must,  in  conclusion,  beg  the  reader 
to  remember,  as  some  extenuation  of  any  short-comings 
he  may  find,  that  this  little  work  only  professes  to  be 
a  "  handbook  "  to  the  study  of  the  subject,  and  not  an 
exhaustive  treatment  of  it. 

It  should  also  be  stated  that  I  have  been  ably  assisted 
by  Mr.  Davison's  compilation  of  the  excellent  index 
which  concludes  the  work. 


HANDBOOK 

TO  THE 

HISTORY  OF  PHILOSOPHY. 


GENERAL  INTEODUCTION. 

I.  What  is  Philosophy? 

Man  finds  himself  conscious  of  being  in  a  ready-made 
world,  of  which  he  forms  part  and  parcel.  He  apprehends 
this  fact  long  before  the  impulse  arises  in  him  to  compre- 
hend it.  He  is  aware,  that  is  to  say,  of  this  world  in  its 
concrete  actuality,  long  before  he  feels  himself  driven  to 
try  and  become  aware  of  it  in  its  abstract  possibility. 
ted  But  this  impulse  nevertheless  arises  at  a  certain  stage 
1  of  man's  development,  and  the  result  is  philosophy,  which 
may  be  described  as  the  offspring  of  the  conscious  endeavour 
to  reconstruct  the  given  world  of  perceptive  experience — 
the  world  found  constructed  in  actuality — according  to  its 
possibility.  This  enormous  and  all-embracing  problem,  as  a 
matter  of  course,  exhibits  a  variety  of  aspects,  and  has 
naturally  been  approached  by  many  paths.  The  History 
of  Philosophy  shows  us  these  aspects  as  they  progressively 
unfold  themselves  to  the  human  mind,  and  the  various 
paths  that  have  been  struck  out  for  their  investigation, 
one  or  two  proving  highways,  many  byways,  and  not 
a  few  blind  roads. 

The  first  aspect  under  which  the  problem  presented 
itself  in  ancient  Greece,  whose  philosophical  develop- 
ment may  be  taken  as  typical,  was  that  of  Being  or 
existence;  the  statement  was — to  discover  the  ultimate 
constituent  of  the  physical  universe.  In  the  next  stage, 
the  problem  became  refined.    It  was  no  longer  an  ultimate 


2  HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  [Introd. 

cosmical  principle  that  was  sought  for,  but  the  ultimate 
form  of  existence  was  conceived  as  one  of  which  the  world  of 
sense  was  a  mere  mode,  if  it  were  not  indeed  opposed  to  it. 
The  problem  of  philosophy  continued  to  be  attacked  on  the 
side  of  being  from  these  two  points,  the  concrete  and  the 
abstract,  until  the  Sophistic  Revolution  which  issued  in 
Socrates,  when  the  standing-ground  was  radically  changed. 
It  was  now  seen  for  the  first  time  that  inasmuch  as 
the  possibility  of  formulating,  much  more  of  solving  the 
problem  of  the  Being  of  the  sensible  world,  presupposed  the 
capacity  of  Knowing,  the  first  step  in  philosophy  must  be 
an  investigation  of  the  conditions  under  which  this  know- 
ledge comes  to  pass,  in  other  words,  an  examination  of 
the  capacity  of  knowing,  itself.  The  philosophical  labours 
of  the  two  typical  thinkers  of  antiquity,  Plato  and  Aristotle, 
were  mainly  occupied  with  this  problem. 

Philosophy  distinguishes  itself  from  mythology  and 
theology,  by  being  essentially  a  conscious  and  reasoned 
efi'ort  to  explain  the  universe,  while  mythology  and  theo- 
logy are,  at  least  in  their  genesis,  essentially  the  uncon- 
scious and  spontaneous  results  of  a  primitive  imagination, 
which  employs  the  notion  of  volition  and  personality  as 
the  basis  of  causal  condition.  The  fact  of  their  being  at 
a  later  stage  refined  and  presented  in  a  quasi-philosophised 
guise,  or  supported  by  philosophical  arguments,  does  not 
alter  their  intrinsic  character. 

The  radical  distinction  between  philosophy  and  special 
science  lies  in  that  while  the  latter  is  concerned  either 
with  the  classification  and  description  of  certain  isolated 
groups  of  phenomena,  or  with  formulating  the  real  or 
causal  conditions  of  the  possibility  of  these  groups  con- 
sidered jjer  se,  the  former  is  occupied  with  the  t  )tality  of 
all  phenomena,  either  as  concerns  its  real  conditions  in 
time  (cosmology  and  psj^chology),  or  its  elemental  conditions, 
i.e.  the  conditions  of  its  possibility  (metaphvsic  proper).* 
Science  is  concerned  with  a  part  for  itself  alone,  while 
philosophy,  if  it  concerns  itself  with  any  part  or  isolated 
group  of  phenomena  at  all,  only  regards  it  in  its  relation 

*  Of  the  di-tinction  between  real  and  elemental  conditions,  we  sliall 
have  occasion  to  treat  more  at  length  in  a  subsequent  division  of  the 
J)  resent  work. 


Introd.]  I.    WHAT  IS   PHILOSOPHY?  3 

to  the  whole,  or  as  a  necessary  propaadeutic  to  a  coherent 
view  of  the  whole. 

The  word  philosophy  tradition  states  to  have  been  fiist 
used  by  Pythagoras.  This  semi-mythical  2:)ersonage,  ac- 
cording to  the  Avell-known  legend,  when  asked  by  Leon, 
the  tyrant  of  Phloeus,  what  vocation  he  followed,  replied 
that  he  had  none,  but  that  he  was  a  philosopher.  On 
being  interrogated  as  to  the  meaning  of  the  woid,  he 
replied,  that  as  in  the  Olympic  Games  some  sought  glory, 
others  gain,  while  others,  more  noble,  came  to  enjoy  the 
spectacle ;  so  in  life,  while  there  were  many  prepared  to 
work  for  honour,  many  for  riches,  there  were  yet  a  few 
who,  despising  all  these  things,  found  their  occupation  in 
the  contemplation  and  knowledge  of  nature  and  man,  and 
that  these  were  the  philosophers. 

In  the  dialogue  Euthydemus,  Plato  defines  philosophy 
aTi(rL<;  ivLaT-^/xr]<i.  It  is  concerned  alone  with  the  ideal^ 
and  is  identical  wdth  ivisdom,  as  opposed  to  opinion,  the 
subject-matter  of  which  is  the  sensible.  Aristotle  some-: 
times  employs  the  term  in  a  general  sense,  so  as  to  include 
all  science,  but  retains  its  narrower  signification  for  what 
would  now  be  termed  Ontology,  namely,  the  science  of 
Being,  in  itself,  as  opjDOsed  to  the  subject-matter  of  the 
special  sciences.  The  Stoics  defined  wisdom  (o-o<^ia),  as 
the  science  of  divine  and  human  things,  but  philosophy 
(<^tA.oo-o<^ta),*  as  the  endeavour  after  perfection,  theoretic 
and  practical,  in  the  three  departments  of  Logic,  Physic, 
and  Ethic.  Philosophy,  with  the  Stoics,  thus  comprehended 
the  whole  range  of  human  interests,  active  no  less  than 
speculative,  but  only  as  a  disposition  of  character,  not  a 
body  of  doctrine,  for  which  the  former  term  was  reserved, 
which  hence  corresponds  properly  to  '  philosophy.'  Epi- 
curus,! in  a  similar  way,  calls  philosophy  the  rational 
endeavour  after  happiness. 

The  above  were  the  leading  definitions  of  the  term  in 
antiquity.  Turning  to  modern  times,  we  find  Christian 
Wolff  enunciating  the  following,  in  his  '  Philosophia 
Kationalis,'  as  an  original  definition  of  philosophical 
knowledge  :  Cognitio  rationis  eorum,  quse  sunt  vel  fiant  unde 

*  Plutarch, '  De  plac.  philosnp.'  i. 

*  '  Empir.  adv.  Math.'  xi.  169. 

B    2 


4  HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY  ?  [Introd. 

intelUgatur  cur  sint  vel  Jiant.  (A  knowledge  of  the  reason 
of  those  things  which  are  or  come  to  pass,  by  which  it  is 
understood  why  they  are  or  come  to  pass.)  Kant  divided 
all  knowledge  into  historical,  cognitio  ex  datis  (knowledge 
through  facts),  and  rational,  cognitio  ex  principiis  (know- 
ledge through  principles).  The  last  was  again  divided 
into  mathematical  knowledge,  through  the  construction 
of  conceptions,  and  philosophical  knowledge,  through 
conceptions  as  such.  The  post-Kantian  definitions  of 
philosophy  in  Germany  have  been  in  most  instances 
based  on  special  systems.  Thus  Herbart  defines  philo- 
sophy^ as  the  working-out  of  conceptions,  this  working- 
out  consisting  in  definition,  classification,  &c.  He  divides 
philosophy  into  three  main  departments :  logic,  meta- 
physic,  and  aesthetic,  the  last-named  including  ethic. 
Schelling  defines  philosophy  as  the  science  of  the  abso- 
lute identity  of  subject  and  object ;  Hegel,  as  the  science 
of  the  absolute,  as  dialectical  movement,  or,  again,  as 
the  science  of  the  self-comprehending  reason.  As  inde- 
pendent definitions  may  be  cited,  Professor  Zeller's  ('  Pre- 
Socratic  Philosophy,'  vol.  i.  p.  8,  of  the  English  trans- 
lation) :  "  Thought  that  is  methodical,  and  directed  in  a 
conscious  manner  to  the  cognition  of  things  in  their  interde- 
pendence." In  Schopenhauer  (Parerga  und  Paralipomena^ 
vol.  ii.  p.  19),  w^e  find  the  following  :  "  Philosophy,  it  is  true, 
has  experience  for  its  subject-matter,  yet  not  like  the 
other  sciences,  this  or  that  particular  experience ;  but 
rather  experience  itself  in  general,  as  such,  according  to 
its  possibility,  its  range,  its  essential  content,  its  internal 
and  external  elements,  its  form  and  matter."  For 
Auguste  Comte,  philosophy  consists  in  the  methodical 
filiation  of  the  special  sciences,  according  to  a  unifying 
conception ;  for  Herbert  Spencer,  it  is  similarly  the 
"  unification  of  knowledge." 

It  may  not  be  out  of  place,  in  an  English  Manual  of 
the  History  of  Philosophy  to  add  a  few  words  respecting 
the  perversion,  and  in  some  cases  the  degradation  the 
word  has  suff'err3d  until  recently  in  this  country. 

It  will  be  seen  that  all  the  definitions  of  "  Philosophy  '* 
we  have  cited  have  this  in  common,  that  they  involve  the 
universal,  as  opposed  to  the  particular,  as  the  subject  of 


Introd.]  I.    WHAT   IS    PHILOSOPHY?  5 

investigation  ;  they  all  imply  the  conditions  of  the  sum  of 
things  as  the  subject-matter  of  inquiry,  either  directly  or 
indirectly.  The  remarks  offered  at  the  commencement  of 
this  section  on  the  scope  of  philosophy  are  sufficiently 
comprehensive  t(j  cover  all  these  definitions,  while  ab- 
stracting from  anything  in  them  which  would  narrow 
the  term  to  any  particular  philosophical  theory. 

The  Englishman,  however,  has  until  recently  indulged 
his  fancy  for  garnishing  his  conversation  with  high- 
sounding  words  by  vulgarising  the  term  philosophy  into 
meaning  any  kind  of  reasoning  on  any  subject  whatever. 
Till  within  the  last  quarter  of  a  century  the  expression 
natural  philosophy  "  figured,  even  in  the  syllabuses  of 
academic  and  learned  bodies,  as  a  designation  for  the 
department  of  scientific  research  known  as  Physics,  while 
to  the  common  man,  chemistry,  astronomy,  physiology, 
were  no  less  "  philosophy." 

We  have  had,  besides,  philosophy  of  manufactures,  of 
love,  of  cookery !  There  is  a  sense,  of  course,  in  which 
the  expressions  "  philosophy  of  history,"  or  "  philosophy 
of  nature,"  may  be  justifiably  employed,  where,  namely, 
history  or  nature,  as  wholes,  are  treated  deductively  in 
the  light  of  a  philosophic  theory  or  conception,  as  part 
of  a  system ;  but  it  is  needless  to  say  that  it  was  not  in 
this  sense  that  such  phrases  were  formerly  employed 
among  the  English-speaking  race.  The  salutary  change 
which  has  taken  place  in  this  respect  within  the  last  few 
years  is  one  more  indication  of  the  opening  up  of  English 
culture  to  continental,  and  especially  German  influences, 
as  well  as  of  the  philosophic  revival  visible  throughout 
English-speaking  communities. 

The  ancient  division  of  philosophy  was  into  Logic, 
Physic  (including  Metaphysic),  and  Ethic.  It  is  said  that 
this  division  had  its  origin  with  the  Stoics.  It  was 
certainly  first  definitely  formulated  by  them.  But  marked 
indications  of  it  are  to  be  found  in  both  Plato  and  Aristotle. 
By  Logic,  or  organon,  was  understood  not  merely  formal 
logic,  but  the  doctrine  of  method  in  general,  including 
theory  of  knowledge  (or  what  answered  as  such  in  the 
ancient  world),  and  to  some  extent  psychology;  under 
physic  was  embraced  cosmical  theory,  as  well  as  ontology, 


6  HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  [Introd. 

in  short,  all  that  pertained  to  the  existence  of  things  as 
such;  while  Ethic  covered  the  whole  range  of  active 
human  interests,  including  politics,  although  its  chief 
problem  was,  in  accordance  with  the  later  Greek  attitude 
of  mind  in  such  matters,  the  discovery  of  the  ideal  of  life 
for  the  individual.  In  the  Middle  Ages,  when  philosophy- 
was  subordinated  to  the  dogmas  of  Christian  theology,  no 
systematic  division  was  made.  In  modern  times  philosophy 
proper  has  been  generally  taken  to  include  logic,  meta- 
physic,  psychology,  and  ethic,  the  "  practical  philosophy  " 
of  the  Germans.  The  usual  ill-fate  that  has  befallen  the 
word  in  Great  Britain,  has  not  been  wanting,  however, 
in  this  connection.  Owing  to  the  special  line  philosophical 
development  took  in  this  island,  to  the  influence,  that  is, 
of  Locke  and  the  Scotch  psychologists,  the  word  showed 
a  tendency  even  where  legitimately  employed  to  become 
narrowed  to  psychology  and  ethic,  or,  as  these  departments 
were  usually  designated,  "  mental  and  moral  philosophy." 
A  not  unnatural  reaction  against  this  view  of  the  scope 
of  philosophy  has  been  recently  exhibited  in  a  desire  to 
exclude  psychology  altogether  from  the  sphere  of  philo- 
sophical studies.  It  has  been  argued  that  mental 
phenomena  being  amenable  in  all  essential  repects  to  the 
inductive  method  employed  in  the  study  of  material 
phenomena,  and  onl^--  differing  in  being  the  object  of 
internal  rather  than  external  observation  (to  use  the 
current  phrase),  there  is  no  reason  for  regarding  their 
treatment  in  any  other  light  than  as  constituting  one 
of  the  special  sciences.  To  this  it  is  replied,  that 
psychological  investigation  has  a  special,  although  in- 
direct bearing  on  "  theory  of  knowledge,"  and  a  fortiori 
on  the  whole  subject-matter  of  philosophy ;  a  bearing 
which  cannot  be  alleged  of  any  objective  science;  that 
only  within  certain  limits  do  the  methods  of  the  ob- 
jective sciences  apply  to  psychology ;  that  "  there  is 
something  in  Mind,  as  the  subject-matter  of  Psych- 
ology, unlike  anything  else,"  and  that  "the  events 
or  states  (however  they  are  called)  which  psychology 
investigates  "  being  "  apprehended  only  in  the  peculiar 
attitude  of  introspection,  makes  a  profound  difference,"&c.* 
*  Professor  Croom  Eobertson  in  '  Mind,'  vol.  viii.  p.  9. 


Introd.]  I.   WHAT  IS   PHILOSOPHY?  7 

It  must  be  admitted,  I  think,  that  a  good  case  is  made  out 
in  these,  and  similar  arguments — in  addition  to  anything 
that  might  be  urged  from  the  universal  practice  of  historj^ — 
for  retaining  Psychology  as  a  department  of  Philosophy. 
But  conceding  this,  it  must  be  none  the  less  recognised  as 
holding  a  position  quite  subordinate  to  the  higher  depart- 
ments, and  the  greater  care  must  be  taken  to  avoid 
introducing  psychological  material  into  them,  and  thus 
obscuring  the  main  issue,  one  of  the  most  fruitful  sources 
of  fallacy  and  confusion.  The  leading  problem  of  philosophy 
is  undoubtedly  "  Theory  of  Knowledge,"  to  discover 
the  conditions  under  which  knowledge,  or  experience,  is 
possible,  in  order  to  re-construct  in  the  forms  of  abstract 
thought  according  to  its  elements,  the  world  given  as 
constructed  in  concrete  intuition. 

The  advances  made  by  science  during  the  latter  half 
of  the  present  century  have  resulted  in  a  striking 
rehabilitation  of  cosmology,  i.e.  the  systematic  doctrine  of 
nature,  or  the  object-world,  as  a  leading  philosophical 
discipline.  The  doctrines  of  the  Conservation  of  Energy 
and  of  Evolution  have  given  to  cosmology  definite  guiding 
principles  for  the  abstract  explanation  of  the  world 
according  to  its  causal  conditions,  which  can  never  be 
taken  from  it,  however  their  application  may  be  modified 
by  subsequent  research. 

The  main  departments  of  philosophic  investigation  are 
these: — (1.)  '■'•  Tlieory  of  knowledge;'^  (2.)  Ontology  (if 
such  be  admitted ;  and  (3.)  Cosmology.  To  these  must  be 
added  as  a  pendent  to  cosmology,  or  the  systematic 
doctrine  of  objective  or  material  nature.  Psychology,  or  the 
systematic  doctrine  of  subjective  or  mental  nature ;  the 
phenomenology  of  the  moral  consciousness  falling  to  be 
dealt  with  by  cosmology  and  psychology  at  their  point  of 
contact  in  sociology.  But  inasmuch  as  all  these  depart- 
ments are  simply  aspects  of  one  reality  to  be  explained — - 
to  wit,  the  totality  of  knowledge — the  great  and  ultimate 
task  of  philosophy  is  to  bridge  over  the  chasms  which 
apparently  divide  them,  to  show  their  interconnection  as 
an  organic  whole,  and  their  ultimate  root  in  the  conditions 
of  knowledge  itself. 


HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  [Intr-qd. 


II.  The  History  of  Philosophy. 

As  we  remarked  at  tlie  commencement  of  the  last 
section,  the  History  of  Philosophy  is  the  history  of  the 
unfolding  to  the  Human  Mind  of  the  various  problems 
involved  in  experience,  and  the  struggles  of  the  reason 
to  resolve  them.  This  has  been  sometimes  attempted 
in  their  entirety,  but  more  frequently  the  necessity 
has  been  felt  of  dealing  with  them  separatel}'-,  and  it 
has  indeed  not  seldom  happened  that  in  the  course 
of  their  isolated  treatment  the  view  of  the  whole  as  the 
end  of  philosophy  has  been  left  out  of  sight. 

An  olDJection  has  been  raised  to  the  history  of  philosophy 
as  an  introduction  to  philosophic  study,  that  in  the  neces- 
sarily condensed  expositions  of  systems  which  are  given,  the 
true  spirit  of  the  founders  is  lost ;  that  the  love  of  research 
and  devotion  to  truth  which  actuated  them,  and  the  steps 
by  which  the  systems  reached  their  ultimate  form,  as  well 
as  the  conflict  of  tendencies  of  which  they  may  be  the 
issue,  can  be  at  best  but  indicated  in  a  dry  and  cursory 
manner.  It  must  be  admitted  that  an  amount  of  truth 
underlies  this  criticism,  especially  as  regards  the  greater 
number  of  actually  extant  histories,  and  even  the  ideal 
history,  whenever  it  shall  appear,  we  can  scarcely  expect 
will  deprive  it  altogether  of  its  point;  but  it  must  we 
think  also  be  admitted  that  though  no  mere  reading  of 
compilations  will  suffice  for  a  serious  philosophic  culture, 
yet  that  such  compilations  are  a  necessary  aid  to  the 
student,  and  further,  that  it  is  possible  for  a  history  of 
philosophy  to  be  presented  in  away  in  which  the  inherent 
drawback  complained  of  may  be  reduced  to  the  minimum. 
"  The  events  which  it  is  most  important  to  comprehend," 
says  Diihring  truly, "  do  not  stare  one  in  the  face."  "  He  who 
will  give  account  of  the  spiritual  working  of  the  greatest 
minds  must  himself  be  capable  of  descending  into  the 
depths."  *  A  history  of  philosophy,  to  be  of  real  use, 
must  not  merely  be  an  abstract  of  doctrines,  but  afford  an 
insight  into  the  historical  and  psychological  genesis  of 
those  doctrines;   and  although  no  history  of  philosophy 

*  Diihring,  'Kritische  Geschichte  der  Philosophie,*  p.  4. 


Introd.1  II.    THE   HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  9 

can  approach  the  first-hand  study  of  the  works  of  philo- 
sophers,* yet  inasmuch  as  it  is  im2:)0ssible  for  any  but 
a  very  small  number  of  students  to  construct  for  them- 
selves even  the  history  of  a  single  period  from  original 
sources,  a  surrogate  is  requisite,  and  need  not  of  necessity 
be  an  altogether  inadequate  one. 

The  history  of  philosophy  has  been  written  mainly 
on  three  different  plans.  There  is  the  compilation-history, 
which  consists  in  a  collection  of  undigested  anecdotes, 
facts,  and  bald,  and  for  the  most  part  loose,  statements  of 
opinion.  Then  there  is  the  tendency-history,  which  reads 
into  the  ideas  of  the  past,  the  doctrines  of  a  modern  system 
or  code  of  ideas;  and,  in  addition,  seeks  for  conformity 
with  the  method  of  this  system  in  the  course  of  historical 
development.  Lastly,  there  is  the  critical-history,  in 
which  a  sjoirit  of  scientific  acumen  and  a  comparative 
criticism  is  brought  to  bear  at  once  upon  the  authorities 
used,  the  doctrines  treated,  and  the  filiation  of  those 
doctrines. 

Of  these  several  plans,  the  first  is  the  most  utterly 
execrable,  and  the  last,  it  need  scarcely  be  said,  the  only 
one  capable  of  furnishing  a  uniformly  reliable  history. 
It  must  not  be  supposed,  however,  that  in  denying  this 
character  of  any  tenderucy-history  as  such,  we  imply  that 
the  history  has  no  tendency ;  for  just  as  general  history 
exhibits  a  certain  determinate  course  of  development,  so 
does  the  history  of  j^hilosophy.  But  the  duty  of  the 
historian,  as  historian,  is  to  maintain  strictly  an  objective 
attitude,  merely  pointing  out  that  element  in  systems 
which  perpetually  recurs — which  in  various  guises  is  unmis- 
takably present — in  all  the  more  important  thinkers,  from 
those  elements  which  are  traceable  to  the  personality  and 
the  age  or  the  country,  while  being  cautious  with  appa- 
rently striking  anticipations  of  modern  thought.  It  is 
perhaps  a  failing  in  most  existing  histories,  that  the 
evolution  of  philosophy  is  too  much  isolated.  It  is  not 
sufficiently  brought  into  connection  with  the  history  of 
civilisation  or  with  historic  evolution  generally.  It  surely 
cannot   but  lie  within  the  province  of  the  historian  of 

*  This  does  not,  of  course,  apply  to  the  fragmentary  works  of  ancient 
authors,  which  require  special  research  and  critical  treatment. 


10  HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  [Introd. 

philosophy  to  trace  the  action  and  reaction  of  speculative 
thought  upon  its  surroundings,  intellectual  and  material. 
Although  we  cannot  expect  to  carry  out  this  principle 
to  its  full  extent  in  a  volume  like  the  present,  an  effort  will 
be  made  to  indicate  the  leading  points  of  contact  between 
the  philosophy  and  the  general  intellectual  conditions  of 
the  several  epochs. 

The  earliest,  and  the  only  ancient  history  of  philosophy, 
in  the  proper  sense  of  the  word,  which  has  come  down  to  us, 
is  that  of  Diogenes  Laertius,  who  wrote  probably  about  the 
third  century.  It  is  a  bad  specimen  of  a  bad  class,  the 
compilation-history,  but  being  one  of  the  most  copious 
sources  of  information  respecting  the  lives  and  characters 
of  the  ancient  philosophers,  has  been  extensively  utilised 
by  all  subsequent  writers.  The  work  of  Diogenes  is, 
however,  so  utterly  uncritical,  and  in  many  respects 
childish,  that  it  requires  to  be  used  with  the  utmost 
caution. 

The  first  modern  history  is  that  of  the  Englishman, 
Thomas  Stanley,  which  wais  originally  published  in  1655, 
and  passed  through  three  editions,  being  re-i&^sued  in  1687 
and  1701.  The  work  is  confined  to  ancient  philosophy, 
and  is  a  mere  compilation  from  Laertius  and  other  classical 
writers.  Contemporaneously  with  Stanley,  a  certain 
Jacobus  Thomasius  published  an  ecclesiastical  and  philo- 
sophical history  combined,  in  Latin,  at  Leipsic.  This  was 
succeeded  in  1697  by  the  great  Dictionnaire  historique  et 
critique  of  Bayle,  which,  although  not  strictly-speaking  a 
history,  nor  concerning  itself  exclusively  with  philo- 
sophical matters,  is  entitled  to  mention,  on  account  of  the 
dimensions  and  importance  of  its  articles  on  the  Greek 
philosophers. 

The  first  history  in  which  modern  philosophy  was 
treated  of  appears  to  have  been  the  Histoire  Critique  de 
la  Philoso])}iie,  in  3  vols.,  by  Deslandes.  (Paris,  17;^0-6.) 
More  important  than  the  last-mentioned  was  the  Historia 
Critica  Philosophise  a  mundo  incunahulis  ad  nostram  usque 
setatem  deduda  Johann  Jakob  Brucker  (5  vols.;  Leipsic, 
1742).  Brucker's  work,  although  by  no  means  critical  iu 
the  modern  sense  of  the  word,  is  an  undoubted  advance 
upon  its  predecessors,  at  once  in  scope,  in  method  and  in 


Introd.]        II.    THE   HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  11 

style.  The  historical  point  of  view  is  certainly  absent, 
but  where  not  clouded  by  prejudice  (for  Brucker  was  a 
tendeucy-writer  of  the  most  pronounced  type),  Brucker 
exhibits  an  amount  of  discernment,  to  be  looked  for  in 
vain  in  previous  wi  iters.  The  standpoint  is  Leibnitzian. 
Brucker's  work  was  condensed  into  English,  by  Enfield, 
and  published  in  a  single  volume  in  1791. 

It  was  succeeded  after  the  lapse  of  a  few"  years  by  an 
Italian  History  of  Philosophy,  by  one  Cromaziano,  subse- 
quently translated  into  German.  Next  came  Tiedemann's 
Geist  der  Speculativen  Philosopkie  (Strasburg,  1791-7). 
This  work  extends  from  Thales  to  Berkeley — the  stand- 
point is  Leibnitz- Wolfian.  Tiedemann  was  the  first  to 
attempt  an  objective  handling  of  the  history  of  philosophy. 
The  method  and  style  of  the  work  is  a  marked  advance 
on  Brucker's,  in  fact  Tiedemann  may  be  looked  upon  as  in 
Tttany  respects  the  founder  of  the  modern  critixsal  history 
of  philosophy.  From  this  time  forward,  histories  of 
philosophy,  and  works  on  the  history  of  philosophy,  form 
a  leading  feature  in  the  literature  of  Germany.  It  will 
be  only  necessary  to  mention  and  characterise  the  most  im- 
portant of  these  treatises.  The  great  Kantian  movement 
produced  several  works  of  the  kind,  partly  of  a  tendency, 
and  partly  of  a  critical  nature.  First  in  order  comes 
Johann  Gottlieb  Buhle's  Lehrhuch  der  Geschichte  der  Philoso- 
phie  (8  vols. ;  Gottingen,  1796-1804).  The  work  is  Kantian, 
leaning  to  the  mystical  tendencies  of  Jacobi  and  his  school. 
The  most  meritorious  of  the  pure  Kantian  histories  is 
that  of  Tennemann,  an  unfinished  work  in  eleven  volumes, 
an  abridgment  of  which  in  English  has  formed  one  of 
the  volumes  in  Bohn's  library.  From  the  standpoint 
of  Schelling,  we  have  Eixner's  Handbuch  der  Geschichte 
der  Philosophie  (3  vols.;  Salzbach,  1822-23).  Ernst  Rein- 
hold's  Handbuch  der  Allgemeinen  Geschichte  der  Philo- 
Sophie  (3  vols. ;  Gotha,  1828-30,)  which  passed  through 
two  or  three  editions,  is  spoken  of  as  meritorious.  But 
the  history  which  until  recently  has  been  unanimously 
regarded  as  the  standard  authority,  not  only  in  Germany, 
but  throughout  Europe,  is  Ritter's  Geschichte  der  Philo- 
sophie (12  vols;  Hamburg,  1829-30:  2nd  ed.  1836-38). 
li  liter's    accurate  scholarship   combined  with  his  impar- 


12  HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  [Introd. 

tiality  to  give  his  work  a  value  likely  to  endure,  in  spite 
of  recent  advances  in  research. 

In  1833,  two  years  after  Hegel's  death,  his  disciple  Karl 
Ludwig  Michelet*  published  his  master's  Lectures  on  the 
History  of  Philosophy,  in  the  collected  edition  of  Hegel's 
works.  Hegel's  history  is  the  most  perfect  representative 
of  the  tendency-history  we  possess.  It  is  based  on  the 
positions  that,  though  every  form  of  historical  reality  has 
its  relative  justification,  there  exists  beside  these  justifi- 
able systems  their  negations,  which  are  not  even  relatively 
justifiable;  that  the  Hegelian  system  forms,  so  far  as 
essentials  reach,  an  absolute  conclusion  to  the  course  of 
historical  development ;  and  that  the  historical  sequence 
of  philosophical  standpoints  must  coincide  .wdth  the  logical 
sequence  of  categories.  These  principles  are  carried  out 
in  the  course  of  the  exposition  with  the  rigour  of  logic, 
and  the  clever  manipulation  of  data  characteristic  of 
Hegel. 

By  far  the  most  popular  history  of  philosophy  is  that 
of  Albert  Schwegier,  in  one  volume.  Since  its  first 
publication  in  1848  it  has  passed  through  nearly  a  dozen 
editions  in  Germany.  It  has  also  been  twice  translated 
into  English  by  J.  H.  Seelye,  in  America,  and  with  an- 
notations by  Mr.  Hutchison  Stirling,  the  last-mentioned 
rendering  being  now  in  its  eighth  edition.  Schwegler's 
work  is  rigorously  impartial,  and  contains  a  mass  of 
closely-packed  information  ;  but  his  presentation  is  some- 
what arid  and  unappreciative.  Of  more  recent  treatises, 
for  the  combination  of  exhaustive  research  and  fulness  of 
detail,  with  critical  appreciation,  Ueberweg's  History,  the 
English  translation  of  which  is  well  known,  occupies  the 
foremost  rank.  The  work  of  Johann  Eduard  Erdmann, 
though  not  so  well  known  in  England,  is  almost  as  much 
read  in  Germany  at  the  present  time.  Erdmann's  literary 
faculty  is  much  greater  than  Ueberweg's.  Among  those- 
treatises  whose  renown  is  as  much  literary  as  philosophical, 
may  be  mentioned  Lange's  '  History  of  Materialism,'  trans- 
lated into  all  the  more  important  European  languages, 
and  in  Germany  become  almost  a  classic,  and  the  small 

*  K.  L.  Michelet  must  not  be  confounded  with  Jules  Michelet,  the 
eminent  French  historian  and  essayist. 


Lntrod.]         II.    THE    HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  ]3 

GescMclite  der  Philosophie  Jcritisch  dargestellt  of  Duliring. 
The  latter,  although  so  far  as  we  are  aware  untranslated  at 
present,  is  as  remarkable  for  the  brilliancy  and  clearness 
of  its  style  as  for  its  strongly  marked  tendency-character. 

The  Latin  nations,  not  excepting  France,  have  failed  in 
achieving  great  original  research  in  the  history  of  philo- 
sophy. Among  the  principal  modern  French  treatises  on 
the  subject  may  be  mentioned  Degerando's  Histoire  comparee 
des  Si/stemes  de  la  Philosojjhie  (4  vols. ;  Paris,  1822-3). 
J.  F.  Nourrisson's  Tableau  des  progres  de  la  pensee  humaine 
de  Thales  jusqiia  Hegel  (Paris,  1858).  Laforet's  Histoire  de 
la  Philosophie  (Brussels  and  Paris,  1867).  Alfred  Weber's 
Histoire  de  la  Philosophie  Europeenne ;  Alfred  Fouillee's 
Histoire  de  la  Philosophie  (Paris,  1874).  The  best-known 
French  history  is  Victor  Cousin's  Histoire  Generale  de  la 
Philosophie  depuis  les  temps  les  plus  recides  Jusqu'a  la  fin  du 
xviii^  siecle  (5th  ed. ;  Paris,  1863).  The  few  Italian  and 
{Spanish  treatises  do  not  call  for  any  special  notice. 

The  first  English  history  of  philosophy,  after  Stanley's , 
was  the  execrable  compilation  from  Brucker  by  William 
Enfield,  first  published  towards  the  close  of  the  last 
century.  This  was  followed  by  Johnson's  translation  of 
Tennemann's  small  manual  (subsequently  reprinted, 
with  additions  and  annotations,  in  Bohn's  Philosophical 
Library).  Robert  Blakey's  '  History  of  the  Philosophy 
of  Mind'  appeared  in  1848;  and  shortly  after  the  late 
F.  D.  Maurice's,  so  far  as  style  is  concerned,  cleverly 
written  '  History  of  Moral  and  Metaphysical  Philosophy.' 
But  more  widely  read  than  any  of  these  was  the 
'  Biographical  History  of  Philosophy '  of  the  late  George 
Henry  Lewes,  first  published  in  1845,  in  four  pocket 
volumes,  and  expanded  in  1867  (2nd  ed.,  revised  1871) 
into  '  The  History  of  Philosophy  from  Thales  to  Comte,' 
n  two  thick  volumes  (crown  8vo.).  Lewes,  who  writes 
nore  j)articularly  from  the  stand^^oint  of  the  Philosophie 
oositive,  but  generally  from  that  of  English  empiricism, 
urnishes  an  example  of  a  probably  unique  development 
of  the  tendency-history,  to  wit,  the  didactic-history. 
There  is  no  positive  reading  of  the  author's  own  position 
nto  the  systems  of  older  thinkers,  or  distortion  of  those 
systems  in  the  course  of  their  development,  as  in  the  ten- 


14  HISTOKY   OF   PHILOSOPHY.  [Lvtrod. 

dency-history  proper,  but  they  one  and  all  serve  as  foils  to 
the  superior  wisdom  of  the  empirical  philosophy  in  general, 
and  the  positive  philosophy  in  particular.  This  is  their  only 
purpose  save  in  so  far  as  they,  here  and  there,  show  weak 
and  faltering;  adumbrations  of  the  "  one  true  method." 

To  Mr.  Hutchison  Stirling's  highly  successful  trans- 
lation of  Schwegler  reference  has  already  been  made. 
The  latest,  and  perhaps  most  important  contribution  to 
works  in  English  on  the  general  histor}^  of  philosophy 
is  the  translation  of  Ueberweg's  work,  published  a  few 
years  since  by  Messrs.  Hodder  &  Stoughton.  The  present 
work,  although  limited  in  point  of  size,  it  is  our  aim  to 
render  as  complete  as  possible  in  all  points  essential  to 
the  student,  while  omitting  unimportant  details. 


(     15     ) 


THE   ORIENTALS. 


At  the  outset  of  the  history  of  philosophy,  as  of  other 
depai  tments  of  culture,  we  are  confronted  with  the  pre- 
historic region  occupied  by  the  primitive  theocratic  civili- 
sations of  the  Oriental  world,  of  Egypt  and  Asia.  The 
view  largely  prevalent,  at  the  end  of  the  last  and  begin- 
ning of  the  present  century,  was  that  these  social 
organisations  were  the  surviving  monuments  of  a  high 
primitive  culture.  In  the  light  of  the  scientific  con- 
ception of  history,  to  which  modern  research  and  criticism 
has  accustomeii  us,  they  are  seen  to  be  cases  of  arrested 
development,  or  of  premature  decay.  The  evolutionary 
principle  in  them,  s  >  to  speak,  their  capacity  for  spon- 
taneous development  and  progress,  exhausted  itself  before 
the  birth  of  that  great  world-evolution  constituting  the 
Ihistory  of  Humanity  jn'oper,  and  of  which  ancient 
Greece  and  modern  Europe,  with  its  colonies,  are  the 
extreme  terms.  The  sixth  century  before  Christ,  or 
thereabouts,  the  age  of  Gautama,  Confucius,  Zoroaster 
and  Thales,  is  the  dawn  of  history  in  the  latter  sense. 
The  history  of  the  modern  world  is  closely  and  de- 
finitely knitted  to  that  of  the  Middle  Ages,  and  this  again 
tc»  the  history  of  ancient  Greece  and  Rome,  the  whole 
forming  an  organise!  system.  But  the  direct  influence 
upon  the  classical  civilisations  of  those  of  Assyria,  Baby- 
lonia, Palestine,  China,  India,  or  even  Egypt,  is  at  best 
obscure.  For  this  reason  we  do  not  purpose  dwelling  at 
any  length  on  the  quasi-philosophies,  or  more  properly 
theosophies,  of  the  East. 

It  is  probable  that  a  considerable  body  of  theosophic  lore 
was  enshrined  in  the  Egyptian  temples  ;  but  encased  as  it 


16  HISTORY   OF   PHILOSOPHY. 

was  in  mythological  language,  and  coming  to  ns  as  most 
of  it  does  through  Greek  sources,  it  is  impossible  to  give 
anything  approaching  a  coherent  and  correct  view  of  its 
general  features.  The  Semitic  race,  on  the  other  hand, 
has  never  in  any  of  its  branches  produced  an  original 
philosophic  or  even  theosophic  system  of  its  own.  The 
Semitic  mind  is,  in  its  pure  state,  anti-philosophical. 
Though  it  has  given  to  the  world  no  less  than  three 
important  ethical  religions,  we  search  in  vain  through  the 
whole  body  of  pure  Semitic  literature,  that  is,  such  as 
reflects  the  Semitic  intellect  unaffected  by  non-Semitic 
culture  (e.g.  the  Hebrew  Scriptures  and  the  Koran),  for  a 
single  trace  even  of  a  philosophic  thought,  much  less  a 
sj'stem,  unless  indeed  we  choose,  as  some  have  done,  to  read 
a  metaphysical  meaning  into  the  old  Hebrew  formula,  "  I 
am  that  I  am  " — the  general  character  and  isolated  position 
of  which,  however,  would  give  colour  to  the  hypothesis 
of  an  Eg5q3tian  origin.  The  fragments  of  reputed  Assyrian 
and  Akkadian  literature  are  likewise  entirely  destitute 
of  a  philosophical  side.  In  the  Medo-Persian  literature, 
as  that  of  an  Aryan  race,  we  might  naturally  expect  to 
find  something  like  a  philosophy,  and,  in  fact,  the  latter 
portions  of  the  Zend-Avesta  show  attempts  to  render  the 
theological  doctrine  of  the  dual  principle  philosophic. 
But  there  is  even  here  no  sign  of  an  independent 
and  original  philosophical  movement.  In  China  the  only 
ancient  writing  possessing  any  speculative  interest  is  that 
of  Lao-tse,  born  B.C.  604,  and  the  main  position  of  which 
is  practically  identical  with  that  of  Indian  Metaphysic, 
though  alleged  to  have  been  uninfluenced  by  it ;  but 
there  is  much  in  the  treatise  of  a  purely  theological 
character,  and  devoid  of  all  philosophic  interest. 

It  is  in  India,  that  we  first  find  a  distinct  and  unmis- 
takable philosoydiic  development.  In  the  sixth  century 
before  Christ,  when  the  non- Aryan  monarchies  of  Egypt, 
Phoenicia,  Babylonia,  and  Assyria,  were  sinking  into 
decay,  and  their  empires  fast  becoming  disintegrated  by 
foreign  influences,  the  Hindoos  felt  the  thrill  of  that 
mighty  wave  of  energy  heralding  the  birth  of  the  new 
human  consciousness — moral,  intellectual,  and  religious 
— which  was  consequent  on  the  decline  of  the  earliest 


THE    ORIENTALS.  17 

forms  of  civilisation.  But  the  philosophic  development 
of  India  is  deprived  of  the  interest  vv^hich  would  other- 
wise attach  to  it,  owing  to  its  separation  from  that  of 
the  main  trnnk  of  the  historic  races,  and  its  consequent 
crudity  and  limitation  in  scope. 

The  sacred  philosophy  (so-called)  of  India  is  contained 
in  the  Upanischads,  or  third  section  of  the  Vedic  scrip- 
tures. Their  main  thesis  consists  of  the  monistic  idea  of 
the  one  true  existent  Absolute,  spoken  of  variously  under 
the  names  of  Paramathman,  Brahman,  as  opposed  to  the 
world  of  falsity  and  appearance,  or  the  Maya.  The  Maija 
is  the  negation  of  Brahnan.  In  itself.  Brahman  is  unthink- 
able and  undifferentiated  in-ness  of  Being  ;  only  through 
the  illusion,  or  the  Maya,  does  it  become  conscious,  mutable, 
undividualised.  "  As  the  colours  in  the  flame  or  the 
red-hot  iron  proceed  therefrom  a  thousandfold,  so  do  all 
beings  proceed  from  the  Unchangeable,  and  return  again 
to  it."  "  As  the  web  issues  from  the  spider,  as  little 
sparks  proceed  from  fire,  so  from  the  one  soul  proceed  all 
living  animals,  all  worlds,  all  the  gods  and  all  beings." 
"  Two  birds  (the  Paramathman,  the  universal  soul,  and 
Jivathman,  the  individual  soul)  inhabit  the  same  tree 
(abide  in  the  same  body),  &c." 

"  As  from  a  blazing  fire  substantial  sparks  proceed  in  a 

thousand  ways,  so  from  the  imperishable  various  souls  are 

produced,  and  they  return  to  him."  These,  and  numberless 

other  passages  of  similar  purport,  are  to  be  found  scattered 

throughout  the  Upanischads.     The  one  theme  is  varied  in 

a  hundred  different  ways,  but  its  substance  is  the  same. 

This  Metaphysic  of  the  Upanischads,  as  will  be  readily 

seen,  is,  to  the   last  degree,  abstract.     No   modus  vivendl 

exists  between  the  Absolute  One  and  the  world  of  "  many- 

hued  reality  " — between  the  real  and  the  non-real.     The 

practical  consequence  of  this  is  an  Ethic  of  Asceticism, 

which  has  absolute  indifference  and  passivity  for  its  ideal 

f  life. 

A  little  later  than  the  Upanischads,  which  are  for  the 

ost  part  poetic  in  character — and  rather  semi-conscious 

ttempts  to  picture  the  mystery  vaguely  felt,  than  con- 

cious  efforts  to  explain   it — come   the  six   philosophical 

ystems — properly   so-ealled.     Their  dates    are  supposed 

c 


18  HISTOKY  OF   PHILOSOPHY. 

to  lie  between  the  fourth  and  fifth  centuries  before  Christ. 
The  first  in  order  is  the  Nyaya,  founded  by  Gotama ;  the 
second,  the  VaiseJiiJca  of  Kanada ;  the  third,  the  Sdnkhya 
of  Kapila;  the  fourth,  the  Yoga  of  Patanjali;  the  fifth, 
the  Mimdnsd  of  Jaimini ;  and  the  sixth,  the  Veddnta  of 
Badarayana  or  Vyasa.  These  systems  are  given  in  the 
form  of  Sutras  or  Aphorisms.  The  Nyaya  is  essentially  a 
system  of  Logic,  It  deals  at  length  with  the  proposition, 
the  syllogism,  the  category,  the  predicable,  &c.  The 
VaiseshiJca  is  a  supplementary  development  of  the  Nyaya, 
but  in  addition  to  its  elaboration  of  the  categories  fur- 
nished in  the  former,  it  contains  a  definite  cosmology  of 
an  atomistic  character.  The  resemblance  of  this  to  the 
Greek  atomism,  and  even  in  some  respects  to  that  of 
modern  science,  is  striking.  The  foundation  of  the 
SanMiya  philosophy  is  a  Monism,  which  in  the  course  of 
the  system  issues  in  a  species  of  Dualism.  The  distinction 
between  matter  and  spirit  is  insisted  upon ;  it  being 
laid  down  as  an  axiom  that  the  production  of  mind  from 
matter,  as  of  something  from  nothing,  is  an  absurdity. 
The  Sankhya  also  contains  a  systematic  theory  of  Emana- 
tion. The  Yoga  is  a  kind  of  pendant  to  the  Sankhya. 
Its  bearing  is  mainly  practical.  It  treats  of  the  means  by 
which  the  individual  soul  may  attain  union  with  the 
universal  soul,  these  means  being  asceticism  of  the  most 
drastic  description.  In  the  Mimansa  we  have  no  properly 
philosophical  doctrine  taught,  and  indeed  its  claim  to 
rank  among  the  philosophical  systems  rests  solely  on  its 
logical  method.  Its  central  idea  is  the  deification  of  the 
Veda  and  Vedic  ritual.  It  is  opposed  to  both  rationalism 
and  theism,  the  Veda  being  the  supreme  authority.  The 
Vedanta  is  really  little  more  than  an  expansion  of  the 
doctrines  of  the  Upanischads  of  the  one  Substance 
Brahma  realised  in  the  world,  or  more  accurately  the  one 
really  existent  Brahma  manifested  in  the  world  of  illusion 
and  plurality,  to  which,  at  most,  a  practical  existence  can 
be  ascribed.  The  personal  soul — the  Jivatliman — through 
ignorance  mistakes  itself  and  the  world  for  real  things. 
Once  it  is  set  free  from  this  ignorance,  and  arrives  at  a 
proper  understanding  of  the  truth,  the  illusion  vanishes, 
and  it  sees  the  identity  of  itself  and  the  woiid  with  the 


en 
iiji 
late 
ffler 
iieD( 
Tlie 
.air 
tlie 
too( 
parti 
Id 

"ini 
tion  1 
\n\ 


THE   ORIENTALS.  19 

universal  soul,  the  one  Paramathman.  As  will  be  appa- 
rent, wellnigh  the  whole  theosophy  and  philosophy  of 
India  turns  upon  a  more  or  less  poetically  expressed 
Monism.  Its  drawback  consists  in  the  fact  that  it  is 
abstract,  and  incapable  of  furnishing  a  coherent  and 
logically  determined  view  of  conscious  reality  as  a  whole, 
and  also  from  its  vague  and  mystical  character,  which 
V  precludes  scientific  deduction  of  the  data  of  consciousness 
fvom  the  outset.  Besides  the  six  dogmatic  systems  we 
haze  noticed,  the  Hindoos  possess  an  empirical,  sceptical, 
and  materialist  school  in  that  of  Carvaka  and  his  followers, 
whose  doctrines  and  even  their  mode  of  statement  bear  a 
close  resemblance  to  those  of  La  Mettrie,  and  the  French 
rationalism  of  the  last  century.  Some  also  reckon  the 
eclectic  Pantheistic  doctrine  contained  in  the  Bhagavad- 
gita,  as  forming  a  distinct  system. 

In  reviewing  the  prehistoric  civilisations,  that  is,  such 
as  are  found  complete  in  all  essentials  at  the  dawn  of 
history,  and  even  then  laying  claim  to  a  remote  antiquity, 
we  find  that  the  great  awakening  of  the  sixth  century 
(circa)  passed  over  some  of  them  without  response.  Of 
this  class  are  the  Egyptian,  Assyrian,  Chaldean,  and 
Phoenician,  with  probably  the  Lydian  and  other  civilisa- 
tions of  Asia  Minor.  Others  again,  such  as  the  Aryan 
civilisations  of  Hindoostan  and  Persia,  and  to  a  lesser 
extent  that  of  China,  responded  to  the  impulse  of  the  new 
movement;  but  the  results  of  the  awakening  sooner  or 
later  became  crystallised,  thus  resolving  themselves  into 
mere  accretions  on  the  previously  existing  culture,  which 
hence  speedily  relapsed  into  its  former  state  of  stagnation. 
The  first  had  lost  their  independent  vitality  ere  history 
dawned.  The  second  had  enough  vitality  to  respond  to 
the  impulse  agitating  the  world  around  them,  but  were 
too  old  and  set  for  its  influence  to  be  more  than  very 
partial. 

In  contrast  to  these  ancient  Oriental  civilisations  already 
"  in  the  sere  and  yellow  leaf,"  we  find  the  Greek  civilisa- 
tion bursting  into  life,  and  forming  the  focus  of  the  newly 
iwakened  individual  consciousness.  Here  there  was  a 
culture  forming,  and  not  fixed  into  a  more  or  less  rigid 
groove.     Hence  with  the  Greece  of  the  sixth  century  and 

c  2 


20  HISTOEY   OF   PHILOSOPHY. 

its  colonies,  we  enter  on  the  history  of  the  main  stream  of 
human  development.  There  is  no  longer  the  tendency  to 
universal  crj^stallisation,  discoverable  in  all  the  prehistoric 
civilisations  of  the  East.  Henceforth  the  ever-widening 
stream  never  becomes  completely  frozen  over.  There  is 
always  a  channel  left  for  the  currents  of  progress.  For 
this  reason,  it  is  only  in  so  far  as  the  ancient  civilisations 
acted  or  were  reacted  upon  by  the  European  civilisation  of 
the  classical  nations,  or  that  of  their  successors,  that  they 
have  any  real  historical  as  distinguished  from  anthropological 
significance.  In  concluding  the  present  section,  we  may 
observe  that  philosophy,  as  the  product  of  a  conscious 
effort  to  explain  the  world,  cannot  be  said  to  have  existed 
prior  to  the  awakening  of  the  human  mind  to  definite 
consciousness  of  itself.  Xot  until  man  cleUherately  iormulsbtedL 
to  himself  for  their  own  sal^e,  and  not  to  subserve  religious 
or  other  ends,  the  problems.  What  am  I  ?  What  is  my 
relation  to  the  world  ?  AYhat  is  the  principle  of  the  world  ? 
can  he  be  said  to  have  begun  to  philosophise.  Hence  we 
may  fairly  deny  the  title  philosophy  to  any  such  theories 
of  the  world,  as  the  theogonies,  cosmogonies,  and  theo- 
sophies  which  obtained  previously  to  this  epoch.  In  no 
ancient  country  do  we  find  an  original  movement  of  a 
philosophic  character  outside  Greece  with,  as  we  have  seen, 
the  solitary  excejDtion  of  India.  But  in  India  the  move- 
ment was  but  of  short  duration,  and  has  exercised  compara- 
tively little  influence  on  history.  We  pass  on,  therefore, 
to  a  consideration  of  the  first  period  of  Greek  philosophy. 

As  among  the  best  authorities  for  Oriental  thought,  apart  from  the 
ancient  books  themselves  in  their  various  translations,  may  be  men- 
tioned, for  the  Egyptians,  Gardner  Wilkinson's  '  Ancient  Egyptians,' 
and  Buusen's  '  Egypt's  Place  in  Universal  History.'  For  the  Chinese, 
Pauthier's  Esquisse  (Vune  histoire  de  la  Philosopliie  chinoise,  and 
Plath's  Eeh'gion  tind  ddtus  der  alien  Cliinesen.  Among  the  numerous 
works  on  the  Indians.  Monier  Williams's  '  Indian  Wisdom,'  contains  a 
good  account  of  Indian  thought;  also  Colebrooke's  'Essays  on  the 
Philosophy  of  the  Hindoos,' in  his  'Miscellaneous  Essays';  various 
translations  of  the  Eoyal  Asiatic  Society ;  and  Earth's  '  Religions  of 
India,'  which  gives  an  excellent  general  view  of  the  subject ;  for 
Buddhism,  may  be  cited  the  various  Eeview  and  other  articles  of 
Mr.  Pthys  Davids ;  Burnouf's  Introduction  a  Vhistoire  du  Bouddhissme 
indien;  and  Spencer  Hardy's '  Legends  and  Theories  of  the  Buddhists,' 


(     21     ) 


GEEEK   PHILOSOPHY 


INTEODUCTION. 

In  Greek  philosophy  there  are  six  well-marked  periods.  (I.) 
that  of  the  Pre-Socratic  Schools  ;  (II.)  the  period  of  Socrates 
and  what  are  commonly  termed  the  imperfect  Socratists  ; 
(III.)  the  culminating  epoch  of  Greek  thought  in  Plato  and 
Aristotle ;  (IV.)  the  commencement  of  its  specialisation, 
and  decline  with  the  Stoics,  Epicureans  and  the  various 
Sceptical  schools  ;  (V.)  the  period  subsequent  to  the  Eoman 
conquest  characterised  by  the  recrudescence  of  the  earlier 
pre-Socratic  doctrines,  or  what  may  be  termed  the  anti- 
quarian period;  and  (VI.)  the  period  of  Neo-Platonism. 
with  which  ancient  philosophy  closes.  Respecting  this 
arrangement,  it  may  be  desirable  to  remark  that  I  have 
filiated  the  imperfect  Socratic  schools  directly  on  to 
Socrates,  in  preference  to  placing  them  after  Plato  and 
Aristotle,  for  the  reason  that  they  seem  more  immediately 
the  outcome  of  the  actual  Socratic  teaching,  so  far  as 
it  has  come  down  to  us.  With  the  Cyrenaics,  the 
Cynics,  the  Megarics,  the  chief,  where  not  the  sole 
subject-matter  of  philosophy,  remains,  as  with  Socrates, 
ethical;  the  teaching  was  mainly  oral,  while,  generally 
speaking,  the  doctrines  themselves  are  directly  traceable  to 
utterances  or  actions  of  the  historical  Socrates.  Plato  and 
Aristotle,  on  the  other  hand,  cannot  be  said  to  have  received 
more  than  an  impulse  from  Socrates.  It  is  next  to  certain 
that  they  could  not  have  obtained  a  single  speculative 
doctrine  from  their  master,  while  the  extent  to  which  the 
dialectical  method  of  Plato's  dialogues  is  attributable  to 
Socrates  or  Plato  himself,  is,  and  will  probably  remain,  a 
matter  of  dispute.  In  both  Plato  and  Aristotle,  philosophy, 
which  Socrates  had  expressly  subordinated   to  practical 


22  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  i. 

issues,  is  extended  to  the  widest  speculative  questions — 
questions  which,  so  far  as  we  know,  never  even  occurred 
to  Socrates,  as  they  had  certainly  not  occurred  to  his 
predecessors. 

After  the  great  original  achievements  of  these  two 
giant  thinkers,  Greek  thought  ceased  to  be  productive, 
and  confined  itself  to  the  reproduction  and  development  of 
pre-Socratic,  Socratic,  Platonic,  or  Aristotelian  doctrines  ;  in 
the  end  absorbing  Oriental  theosophy.  The  pre-Socratic 
philosophy  falls  under  two  sections ;  the  first  comprising 
what  are  usually  known  as  the  Ionian,  the  Italian,  and 
the  Eleatic  schools  ;  and  the  second  taking  in  Herakleitos, 
Empedokles,  the  Atomists  (Demokritos  and  Leukippus), 
and  Anaxagoras. 

In  considering  these  early  stages  in  the  history  of 
philosophy,  we  must  guard  ourselves  from  reading  into 
systems  ideas  pertaining  to  later  phases  in  the  evolution 
of  thought.  There  is  a  difficulty  for  many  of  us,  ac- 
customed as  we  are  to  modem  rules  of  philosophising, 
in  realising  the  naive  and  crude  fashion  in  which  great 
problems  presented  themselves  to  the  early  thinkers, 
and  the  still  more  crude  attempts  at  solution  which 
satisfied  them.  It  is  essential  to  bear  in  mind,  especially 
in  the  schools  of  our  first  section,  that  distinctions  and 
modes  of  statement,  familiar  to  us  now  as  household 
words,  were  with  them  non-existent — such,  for  instance, 
as  Materialism  and  Idealism,  Theism  and  Atheism,  Subjec- 
tive and  Objective,  Knowing  and  Being,  ]\Iind  and 
Matter.  Hence,  for  example,  it  is  impossible  to  label 
Thales  as  materialist  or  immaterialist,  theist  or  atheist,  and 
the  attempt  to  do  so  only  shows  an  utter  lack  of  historical 
insight.  The  problems,  or  the  aspects  of  problems,  of 
which  these  expressions  connote  the  supposed  solution, 
had  not  as  yet  appeared  above  the  horizon  of  speculation, 
and  hence  this  terminology  is  altogether  devoid  of  meaning. 
The  lonians  were  merely  naive  Hylozoists,  that  is,  they 
simply  took  the  world  as  they  found  it ;  to  them  the  object 
of  external  perception  (as  existent),  being  the  all,  the 
only  thing  standing  in  need  of  explanation.  Accordingly, 
the  problem  was  to  find  the  ultimate  form  of  that  object, 
a  particular  form  from  which  all  other  forms  were  deriva- 


Epoch  I.]  THE    PRE-SOCRATIC   SCHOOLS.  23 

tive.  Thales  pronounced  this  to  be  Water  ;  Anaximenes, 
Air  ;  and  Anaximander,  a  formless  chaos.  They  might,  and 
it  is  likely  enough  did,  believe  in  the  gods  of  their  age  and 
country  ;  but  these  gods,  like  the  souls  of  men  and  demons, 
were  conceived,  no  less  than  the  other  objects  of  the  world, 
as  entities  constituted  of  this  same  primitive  matter.  The 
attitude  of  mind  represented  by  the  early  Ionian  specu- 
lators was  that  of  a  simple  childlike  questioning,  which 
readily  accepts  the  first  answer  that  offers  itself,  and  with 
this  rests  satisfied,  without  waiting  to  test  its  consistency 
even  with  itself,  much  less  with  fact. 

For  Greek  philosophy  in  general,  the  best  work  is  Professor  Eduard 
Zeller's  Philosophie  der  Grieehen,  some  of  the  volumes  of  which  have 
been  published  separately  in  English ;  that  on  the  pre-Socratic  philosophy 
is  translated  by  S.  F.  AUeyne :  also  Dyk's  Versokratische  Philosophie. 
Of  the  ordinary  histories  of  Philosophy,  Ritter's  may  be  mentioned  as 
particularly  full  on  the  pre-Socratic  schools  as  on  ancient  philosophy 
generally.  An  English  translation  of  this  portion  of  Ritter  (in  4  vols.) 
exists,  but  is  now  out  of  print  and  scarce.  Eitter  and  Preller's '  Selection 
of  Fragments '  is  also  a  standai:d  work.  Brandis'  Handbuch  der  Ge- 
schischte  der  GriecMsch-Romische  Philosophie  has  considerable  value. 
No  good  English  work  specially  devoted  to  ancient  philosophy  exists, 
with  the  exception  of  Ferrier's  '  Pre-Socratic  Philosophy.'  Of  the 
numerous  critical  and  antiquarian  essays  in  Latin  and  German  on 
individual  philosophers  and  special  questions  of  scholarship,  only  those 
of  interest  to  the  general  student  will  be  mentioned. 


EPOCH  L— THE  PEE-SOCEATIC  SCHOOLS. 


I.  THE  IONIAN  SCHOOLS. 

Thales. 

Thales,  one  of  the  seven  sages,  is  the  reputed  founder  of 
Greek  philosophy.  He  was  born  about  B.C.  624,  but  the 
exact  date  is  uncertain,  at  Miletus,  whence  his  ancestors 
are  said  to  have  migrated  from  Boeotia.  Of  the  numerous 
saws  attributed  to  him,  and  his  knowledge  of  Mathematics 
and  Astronomy,  it  is  not  necessary  to  speak  at  length.  It 
is  sufficient  to  observe  that  Thales  was  one  of  the  most 
famous  mathematicians  and  astronomers  of  ancient  times, 
is  alleged  to  have   introduced  geometry  to  the  Greeks, 


24  GKEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  ^  [Epoch  I. 

and  to  have  been  the  first  to  foretell  eclipses.  Some  doubt 
exists  as  to  the  authenticity  of  the  story  of  his  Egyptian 
journey,  and  still  more  as  to  his  having  acquired  his  learn- 
ing from  Egyptian  sources.  Little  or  nothing  is  known 
with  certainty  as  to  his  life,  though  there  are  numerous 
legends  respecting  it. 

The  claim  of  Thales  to  be  the  founder  of  philosophy 
rests  on  his  having  been  the  first  to  attempt  to  explain 
the  world  on  a  non-mythological  and  non-theological 
principle.  He  propounded  the  question,  What  is  the  ulti- 
mate substance  to  which  all  things  are  reducible  ?  and 
answered  it  by  asserting  the  primitive  substance  to  be  water. 
How  he  arrived  at  this  conclusion  is  not  known,  nor  indeed 
the  manner  in  which  he  conceived  the  world  to  be  evolved, 
though,  judging  from  the  analogy  of  kindred  systems,  this 
was  by  a  process  of  condensation  and  rarefaction.  There 
have  been  plenty  of  theories  as  to  how  Thales  was  led  to 
his  central  doctrine  (e.g.  Aristotle's,  that  it  was  by  obser- 
ving that  the  seeds  of  all  things  are  moist),  but  they  are 
one  and  all  purely  conjectural.  Various  cosmological  specu- 
lations were  attributed  to  Thales  in  ancient  times,  among 
others,  that  the  earth  was  a  flat  disc  floating  upon  water ; 
that  the  heavenly  bodies  were  glowing  masses;  also 
theories  respecting  the  nature  of  demons,  heroes,  &c. 

All  the  reports  concerning  the  doctrines  of  Thales  are, 
however,  of  so  doubtful  and  contradictory  a  nature,  that  it 
is  impossible  to  assert  anything  with  certainty  respecting 
them,  except  as  concerns  the  cardinal  thesis  of  water  being 
the  principle  of  all  things.  If  we  are  to  believe  some  of 
these  reports,  he  seems  to  have  been  hardl}^,  if  at  all,  eman- 
cipated from  the  animistic  or  fetischistic  attitude  of  mind 
peculiar  to  the  early  stages  of  human  culture ;  but  this 
would  appear  scarcely  compatible  with  those  which 
credit  him  with  a  comparatively  high  degree  of  scientific 
attainment. 

Anaximandros. 

Anaximandros,  or,  as  it  is  usually  Anglicised,  Anaxi- 
mander,  was  also  a  native  of  Miletus,  and  a  younger  con- 
temporar}^  and  some  say  pupil  of  Thales.     The  date  of  his 


Epoch  I.]  THE  PRE-SOCKATIC   SCHOOLS.  25 

birth  is  given  as  B.C.  611.  Nothing  is  known  of  his  life. 
Report  states  that  he  was  also  proficient  in  geography  and 
astronomy ;  that  he  designed  the  first  map  and  celestial 
globe ;  and,  according  to  some,  invented  the  sun-dial,  tlKjugh 
others  attribute  this  to  Thales  or  Pherekydes.  He  un- 
doubtedly wrote  the  first  philosophical  treatise,  its  main 
thesis  being  that  into  that  whence  things  arise,  they  must 
return ;  that  this  primal  substance,  which  he  is  the  first 
to  designate  by  the  word  principle  (apx^)?  is  a  formless 
and  infinite  matter,  incorruptible  and  eternal,  and  that  of 
its  own  inherent  force  things  arise  from  it  and  pass  into 
it  again,  or  perhaps  we  might  say  it  determines  itself  in 
forms  which  either  give  way  to  other  forms  or  lose  all 
form  whatever,  ^.e.  return  again  to  the  primal  indefiniteness. 
The  first  determination  of  primitive  substance  was  heat 
and  cold,  a  fiery  sphere  arising  surrounded  by  cold  air. 
From  fire  and  air  were  formed  the  stars  (Anaximandros 
regarded  the  stars  as  animated  beings  or  divinities, 
according  to  the  view  prevalent  in  ancient  times,  and 
subscribed  to  by  no  less  a  thinker  than  Plato),  in  the  midst 
of  which  floats  the  cylindrically-shaped  earth,  immovable, 
owing  to  its  equidistance  from  all  points  of  the  sur- 
rounding heavens,  which  were  apparently  conceived  as  a 
circumscribed  space  like  the  interior  of  a  hollow  globe. 
The  earth  was  originally  fluid.  Through  the  co-operation 
of  heat  and  moisture  organic  life  originated,  passing  suc- 
cessively into  higher  and  higher  forms.  All  land  animals 
were  primarily  marine  organizations,  becoming  modified, 
and  gradually  assuming  their  present  characters  as  the  con- 
ditions of  their  environment  changed.  As  the  earth  began 
to  dry,  the  fins  gave  place,  among  those  inhabiting  the 
dry  portion  of  its  surface,  to  members  more  adapted  to  life 
under  the  new  conditions.  This  development  from  pre- 
existent  forms  applied  no  less  to  man  than  to  other 
animals. 

A  moot-point  as  regards  Anaximandros  has  been  the 
nature  of  his  primitive  essence.  That  it  was  conceived 
as  material  substance,  few  scholars  of  any  eminence  have 
doubted,  but  some,  like  Bitter,  have  been  found  to  main- 
tain that  its  differentiation  existed  in  it  from  the  begin- 
ning, in  other  words,  that  it  was  an  infinite  aggregate  of 


26  GKEEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. 

determinate  elements  like  the  Jiomoeomoerioe  of  Anaxagoras. 
That  such  an  assumption  is  not  only  unsupported  by- 
evidence,  but  is  foreign  to  the  whole  nature  of  the  specu- 
lation, has  been  conclusively  shown  by  Zeller.  All  the 
accounts  respecting  the  primitive  substance  of  Anaxi- 
mandros  emphasise  the  fact  of  its  absolute  formlessness. 

The  advance  made  by  Anaximandros  upon  Thales  will 
be  apparent  to  the  most  superficial  student.  There  is  little 
doubt  that  Anaximandros  w^as  a  speculative  genius  of  the 
first  order.  Prompted,  in  all  jDrobability,  merely  by 
the  crude  and  disconnected  dicta  of  Thales,  he  constructed  a 
coherent  system  on  the  hylozoistic  basis,  a  system,  consider- 
ing the  then  state  of  knowledge,  possessing  considerable 
plausibility,  and  containing  one  of  the  most  remarkable 
anticipations  of  the  great  cosmological  truth  of  modem 
times  which  history  can  offer.  The  wonderful  guess  of 
Anaximandros  on  the  subject  of  Evolution  must  ever 
maintain  his  name  as  memorable  in  the  annals  of  human 
thought.  It  is  noteworthy  that  this  idea,  if  not  consciously 
deduced  from  his  cardinal  doctrine  of  a  universal  substance, 
infinite  in  quantity  and  indefinite  in  quality  ;per  se,  yet 
possessing  the  inherent  capacity  for  infinite  modification, 
nevertheless,  logically  follows  from  it.  The  forecast 
of  Anaximandros  has  slept  for  two  thousand  years. 
It  first  began  to  awaken  at  the  end  of  the  last  century,  and 
when  in  the  fulness  of  time  it  burst  into  that  richness  of 
life  which  has  so  jorofoundly  influenced  the  thought  of  our 
age,  it  was  no  longer  on  the  shores  of  the  ^gean, 
deserted  by  the  genius  of  speculation  for  many  a  long 
century,  but  in  the  little  village  of  Down  in  Kent.  It  is 
a  remarkable  circumstance,  as  the  late  Dr.  Thirlwall 
observed  ('  History  of  Greece,'  vol.  ii.  pp.  134-5),  that  the 
speculations  of  Anaximandros  were  so  little  followed  up 
by  later  thinkers  of  antiquity,  though  it  may  be  accounted 
for  in  more  ways  than  one. 


Anaximenes. 

The  date  of  Anaximenes'  birth  is  uncertain ;  but  he  was 
probably  a  younger  contemporary  of  Thales  and  Anaxi- 


Epoch  l]  THE   PRE-SOCRATIC   SCHOOLS.  27 

mander,  being  by  some  asserted  to  have  been  a  pupil  of 
the  latter.     He  was,  also,  a  native  of  Miletus. 

Anaximenes  re-affirmed  the  qualitative  character  of  the 
primal  substance,  but  instead  of  identifying  it,  as  Thales 
had  done,  with  water,  asserted  it  to  be  air.  The  working 
out  of  the  system  accorded  with  this  alteration.  As 
Thales  had  conceived  the  earth  to  be  a  flat  disc,  floating 
upon  water,  so  Anaximenes  described  it  as  a  flat  disc, 
floating  upon  air.  The  latter,  however,  definitely  worked 
out  the  notion  of  the  production  of  the  real  world  through 
the  condensation  and  rarefaction  of  the  primitive  element. 
Heat  and  cold  appear  to  have  corresponded  to  this  process 
— heat  representing  rarefaction,  and  cold  condensation. 
Anaximenes  is  reported  as  maintaining  the  production  of 
clouds  from  air,  of  water  from  clouds,  and  of  earth  from 
water.  The  earth  was  the  centre  of  the  universe,  the 
heavenly  bodies,  which  consisted  of  a  mixture  of  earth  and 
fire,  circulating  round  it.  All  things  were  destined  to  be 
ultimately  resolved  into  air. 

The  work  of  Anaximenes  in  which  these  doctrines  were 
propounded,  was  known  to  Aristotle  and  his  pupil  Theo- 
phrastus,  but  appears  to  have  been  lost  soon  after  their  time. 

Diogenes  of  Apollonia. 

A  hiatus  exists  in  the  line  of  the  Ionic  physicists 
between  Anaximenes  and  the  present  philosopher,  the 
last  of  the  school,  only  broken  by  one  or  two  obscure  per- 
sonages, who  are  little  more  than  names,  such  as  Hippo, 
a  follower  of  Thales  and  Idaeus,  who  seems  to  have  been 
influenced  by  Anaximenes. 

Diogenes  is  generally  supposed  to  have  flourished  about 
the  time  of  Anaxagoras.  Very  little  is  known  of  his  life, 
and  even  the  identity  of  his  birthplace,  Apollonia,  is  not 
settled,  but  it  is  generally  referred  to  the  place  of  that 
name  in  Crete,  though  the  fact  that  he  wrote  in  the 
Ionic  dialect,  and  belonged  to  the  Ionic  school,  tends 
to  militate  against  this  supposition.  With  Diogenes  we 
undoubtedly  reach  the  highwater-mark  of  Ionic  specu- 
lation. To  Diogenes,  as  to  Anaximenes,  the  circumambient 
air,  which   seems   to   interpenetrate   all  things,  was   the 


28  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. 

essence  of  which  all  things  consist,  the  primitive  form  of 
matter  of  which  all  other  forms  are  modifications,  and  into 
which  they  must  ultimately  be  resolved.  1'he  great 
philosophic  merit  of  Diogenes  consists  in  his  being  the 
first  to  explicitly  enunciate  the  principle  of  Monism.  His 
predecessors  had,  one  and  all,  assumed  this  principle 
implicitly  at  the  outset,  but  Diogenes  seeks  to  demonstrate 
it.  He  urges  the  inexplicability  of  mutual  action  and 
reaction,  othei-wise  than  on  a  monistic  basis.  He  shows 
that  the  facts  of  nature  and  the  real  world  all  point  to  one 
primitive  substance  as  their  substratum.  This  explicit 
Monism  denotes  a  considerable  advance  in  speculation. 
Another  distinctive  feature  of  the  philosophy  of  Diogenes, 
which  some  would  maintain,  though  perhaps  without 
sufficient  reason,  to  be  not  so  much  a  develoj^ment  on 
older  lines  as  a  change  of  front,  was  the  attribution  of 
intelligence  to  his '  air.'  The  soul,  the  intelligent  element 
in  man,  was  of  course  nothing  but  breath  or  air.  Hence 
the  question  may  have  arisen.  Why  should  not  the  air- 
matter  manifested  as  intelligent  in  us,  be  so  in  its 
essential  nature  ?  Diogenes,  in  his  attempts  to  prove 
this,  gives  us  the  earliest  sample  we  possess  of  the 
design  argument.  At  the  same  time,  we  have  in  the 
doctrine  itself  the  first  distinct  expression  of  the  theory  of 
an  anima  mujidi,  which  has  played  such  an  important  part 
in  subsequent  speculation. 

In  Diogenes  the  Ionian  Physicism  finds  its  culmination 
and  conclusion.  The  school  had  doubtless,  in  his  time, 
fallen  into  disrepute,  and  the  plausibility  and  more  recent 
form  its  fundamental  principles  assumed  under  his  auspices 
failed  to  rehabilitate  it.  Such  was  the  condition  of  philo- 
sophy at  the  time  of  Anaxagoras.  But  as  most  of  these 
early  schools  overlap  each  other,  so  to  speak,  it  is  impos- 
sible to  deal  with  them  chronologically,  and  hence  we  are 
compelled  to  retrace  our  steps,  in  order  to  follow  another 
line  of  speculation,  viz.  the  Pythagorean  or  Italian. 


(    29     ) 


II.  THE  ITALIAN  SCHOOL. 

Pythagoras. 

"  Among  all  the  schools  of  philosophy  known  to  us," 
says  Zeller,  "  there  is  none  of  which  the  history  is  so  over- 
grown, we  may  almost  say  so  concealed  by  myths  and 
fictions,  and  the  doctrines  of  which  have  been  so  replaced 
in  the  course  of  tradition  by  such  a  mass  of  later  con- 
stituents, as  the  Pj^thagorean."  It  is  indeed  impossible 
now  to  disentangle  the  doctrines  of  Pythagoras  himself 
with  any  certainty  from  those  of  members  of  his  school. 
A  still  greater  mystery  overhangs  the  life  of  Pythagoras, 
the  three  biographies  that  have  survived  from  antiquity 
being  altogether  unreliable.  That  Pythagoras  was  the  son 
of  a  stone-cutter,  named  Innesarchus,  and  was  born  at 
Samos,  as  well  as  that  he  was  of  Phoenician  descent,  all  are 
agreed ;  while  his  birth  is  generally  fixed  at  between  B.C. 
680  and  590.  In  his  fortieth  year  he  is  said  to  have  left 
his  home  and  started  on  his  travels,  extending  over  twelve 
years,  in  the  course  of  which  he  visited  Ionia,  Phoenicia, 
and  Egypt,  finally  settling  down  in  the  Greek  city  of 
Crotona  in  Southern  Italy.  There  are,  however,  various  con- 
flicting reports  on  the  age  at  which  he  left  Samos,  and  also 
on  the  duration  of  his  stay  in  the  East,  the  only  unanimity 
being  as  to  his  ultimate  place  of  residence.  In  ancient 
times  Pythagoras  was  commonly  regarded  as  the  main 
original  channel  for  the  introduction  of  Oriental,  and 
es23ecially  Egyptian,  ideas  into  Europe. 

Pythagoras,  soon  after  his  arrival  in  Crotona,  became  a 
political  and  religious  as  well  as  a  philosophical  power 
throughout  the  Greek  colonies  of  Italy.  There  is  eveiy 
indication  of  a  desire  on  his  part  to  establish  a  cult  and 
polity  on  the  model  of  the  Eastern  theocracies.  Thus,  we 
have  the  division  of  doctrine  into  esoteric  and  exoteric, 
with  a  corresponding  distinction  among  its  hearers,  of  the 
introduction  of  mysteries,  the  prohibition  of  sundry  articles 
of  diet,  the  institution  of  a  special  regime  of  life  for  the 
elect  and  such  as  aspired  to  be  so,  and  above  all,  the 
attempt,  for   a  time   more   than    partially  successful,  to 


30  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. 

acquire  a  political  authority  for  himself  and  his  followers, 
amounting  to  the  complete  control  of  the  state. 

The  circumstances  of  the  death  of  Pythagoras  are 
variously  related.  According  to  some  accounts  he  was 
killed  in  one  of  the  civil  tumults  which  ended  in  the 
destruction  of  the  whole  faction,  and  the  massacre  or  dis- 
persion of  its  members ;  according  to  others,  he  died  of 
starvation  at  Metapontum  (about  B.C.  500),  whither  he 
was  compelled  to  fly  to  escape  the  vengeance  of  the 
popular  party.  As  it  is  practically  impossible  to  furnish  a 
reliable  account  of  the  philosophy  of  Pythagoras  himself, 
we  shall  confine  ourselves  to  giving  a  sketch  of  the 
Pythagorean  system  as  it  has  come  down  to  us,  without 
attempting  to  enter  into  moot  points  of  scholarship  as  to 
the  relative  antiquity  of  its  re23uted  doctrines. 

The  Pythagohean  System. 

With  the  Pythagorean  philosophy  we  enter  upon  a  new 
and  more  advanced  j^hase  of  Greek  thought  than  that  of 
the  Hylozoists  of  Miletus.  The  Pythagoreans  were 
evidently  capable  of  a  high  degree  of  abstraction.  The 
principle  and  essence  of  all  things  was  now  no  longer 
conceived  as  concrete,  but  as  abstract. 

The  fundamental  doctrine  attributed  to  Pythagoras, 
that  "  All  is  number,"  must  be  taken  as  meaning  not 
merely  that  everything  can  be  treated  numericall}^  but  that 
number  is  that  by  which  the  constitution  of  things  is 
determined.  In  other  words,  the  matter  as  well  as  the 
form  of  the  real  was  deemed  to  consist  in  number, 
although  the  antithesis  of  matter  and  form  had  not  as  yet 
become  explicit  in  thought.  The  Pythagoreans  were 
probably  led  to  this  theory  by  perceiving  that  all  mathe- 
matical conceptions  are  reducible  to  terms  of  number.  It 
was  most  likely  to  an  attentive  study  of  the  mathematical 
aspects  of  astronomy  and  music,  sciences  which  the  Pjiiha- 
goreans  especially  cultivated,  that  the  doctrine  of  numbers 
is  more  immediately  traceable.  There  is  no  doubt  that  the 
ideas  of  proportion  and  harmony  jjervaded  the  whole 
Pythagorean  sj^stem.  The  world  was  conceived  as  a 
harmoniously  articulated  whole ;  the  doctrine  of  numbers 
was  merely  the  ultimate  expression  of  this  conception,  an 


Epoch  I.]  THE   PRE-SOCRATIO   SCHOOLS.  31 

exj^ression  which  will  a]3pear  natural  enough  when  one 
considers  that  the,  to  us,  familiar  distinction  of  abstract 
and  concrete  had  not  been  made.  This  hypostasis,  then, 
of  numbers  naturally  gave  rise  to  an  emanation-theory. 
'J  hat  whence  all  numbers  are  derivable,  their  source  or 
generative  parent,  as  it  is  termed,  is  the  One  or  Unity. 
From  the  One,  as  their  common  root,  all  numbers  proceed, 
and  inasmu<5h  as  all  numbers  are  contained  therein,  it  is 
often  designated  as  "  the  number."  From  the  One,  there 
issues  the  antithesis  which  plays  so  great  a  part  in  the 
system,  of  the  Indefinite  and  Definite,*  or  the  unlimited 
and  the  limiting,  in  which  perhaps,  we  may  see  a  faint 
adumbration  of  the  later  antithesis  of  matter  and  form. 
Thence  proceeds  the  odd  and  the  even ;  the  even  being 
identified  with  the  indefinite,  and  the  odd  with  the  definite, 
because  the  odd  sets  a  limit  to  bi-partition  which  the 
even  does  not.  The  definite  or  limiting  is  throughout 
regarded  as  the  higher  principle,  but  is  equally  with  its 
correlate  subordinated  to  Unity  or  the  One. 

from  these  main  pairs  (viz.  the  Indefinite  and  the 
Definite,  the  Even  and  the  Odd)  proceed  eight  subordinate 
couples,  which,  with  the  two  primary,  make  up  the  sacred 
number  ten ;  the  complete  Pythagorean  categories  being 
as  follows:  (1)  Definite  and  Indefinite;  (2)  Odd  and 
Even  ;  (3)  Onet  and  Many  ;  (4)  Right  and  Left ;  (5)  Male 
and  Female;  (6)  Resting  and  Moving;  (7)  Straight  and 
Curved ;  (8)  Light  and  Darkness ;  (9)  Good  and  Evil ; 
(10)  Square  and  Oblong.  In  so  far  as  these  contradic- 
tions, immanent  in  the  original  unity,  appear  in  opjDOsition 
to  each  other  outside  this  unity,  arises  the  system  of 
numbers  or  things. 

The  application  of  this  theory  to  the  detailed  expla- 
nation of  the  concrete  world  could  not  be  effected  otherwise 
than  by  a  series  of  arbitrary  combinations,  ae  that  one  is 
the  point,  two  the  line,  three  the  plane,  that  virtue  is  a 
harmony  of  certain  numbers,  &c. 

*  Erdmann  remarks  as  characteristic  that  in  place  of  the  physical 
opposition  of  heat  and  cold  as  with  the  hylozoists,  we  have  here  a 
logical  opposition.    (Erdmann,  vol.  i.  p.  26.) 

t  Tliis  antithetical  unity  was  distinguidhed  from  the  unconditioned 
unity  at  the  basis  of  the  system. 


32  GEEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. 

In  the  Pythagorean  cosmology,  the  universe  was  divided 
into  ten  S23heres,  which  were  regarded  as  revolving  round 
the  central  iire.  The  soul  was  of  course  conceived  as  in 
essence  number ;  and  cognition  as  arising  in  and  through 
number.  That  which  could  not  be  expressed  mathemati- 
cally was  therefore  incognisable  and  nothing. 


The  above  is  of  course  only  a  brief  sketch  of  the 
leading  jDositions  of  a  system  which  exercised  a  vast 
influence  ujion  ancient  speculation,  but  which  nevertheless 
suffered  more  variations  in  the  hands  of  its  individual 
adherents  than  any  other,  for  the  reason  that  its  founder 
committed  nothing  to  writing.  Add  to  this,  that  the 
earliest  Pythagorean  fragments  probably  date  from  a 
century  after  Pythagoras's  time,  and  the  difticulty  of  ar- 
riving at  true  Pythagoreanism  with  certainty,  at  present, 
will  be  sufficiently  apparent. 

It  will  be  seen,  however,  from  what  we  have  said  that 
the  Pythagorean  system  (so-called)  contains  all  the  later 
philosophical  disciplines  in  germ.  Thus  in  addition*  to 
an  ontology  proper,  we  have  the  first  attempt  on  the 
basis  of  this  to  solve  the  problems  of  Theory  of  Knowledge, 
Psychology,  Cosmology  and  Ethics.  These  attempts,  it  is 
true,  are  confined  to  a  few  merely  arbitrary  and  childish 
dicta,  but  still  they  are  significant  as  showing  a  recognition 
of  the  existence  of  these  problems,  and  of  the  duty  of 
philosoph}'  to  explain  them  on  its  fundamental  principles. 

But  it  is  of  the  utmost  importance  to  bear  in  mind  that 
Pythagoreanism  was  primarily  a  religion  and  a  polity, 
and  that  to  this  its  philosophy  was  supposed  to  lead  up  as 
its  end  and  goal.  It  is  in  the  character  of  hierophant, 
rather  than  that  of  philo-opher,  that  the  majestic  and 
semi-mythical  figure  of  Pythagoras  stands  forrh  so  con- 
spicuously in  classical  histor3\  The  remembrance  of  the 
personality  of  the  great  Samian  as  a  religious  leader 
lingered  with  the  world  till  the  last  ray  of  the  afterglow 
of  ancient  culture  had  died  away. 

The  most  interesting  ancient  sources  for  Pj^thagoreanism 
are  the"  Golden  verses,"  with  the  commentai  y  by  Hierokles. 


(33) 


^OLS.  35 


vcver  slight, 
THE  ELEATIC  SCHOOL.     -»  follows  :  If 

st  first  reach 
— »<>. —  ^^   '     next 

^  'nt 

Xenophanes. 

The  reputed  founder  of  the  Eleatic  school  was  born  at 
Kolophon,  in  Ionia.  The  date  of  his  birth  is  uncertain, 
but  he  is  said  to  have  flourished  about  B.C.  530.  He  spent 
the  greater  part  of  his  life  in  travelling,  in  the  manner  of 
an  ancient  baid,  through  the  chief  cities  of  Sicily  and 
Magna  Greecia,  finally  settling  in  Elea,  a  town  of  Southern 
Italy. 

The   burden   of  the  poems  which   Xenophanes,  sung, 
was  that  the  All  or  the  One,  as  it  was  variously  termed, 
was   God.     As    a   pendant   to    this   we   have   a   polemic 
against  the  current  polytheism,  and  the  immorality  of  the 
narratives  of  the  poets.     Some  of  the  fragments  preserved 
would  seem  to  imply  a  theistic  tendency,*  but  others  dis- 
tinctly identify  "  God  "  with  the  spacial  universe.     Thus 
the  statement  that  the  shape  of  the  deity  was  spherical  is 
plainly   an  inference   from    the   apparent   figure   formed 
by  the    sky  and   horizon.     Passionless,  without  motion, 
neither   limited    nor    unlimited,    "  all   eye,   all    ear,    all 
thought,"    such  was  the  God,    Being,    or  All,    of  Xeno- 
phanes.     It   is   the   enunciation   of   unity   and   change- 
lessness  as  the  attributes  of  true  Being  against  the  multi- 
plicity  and   change  of  the  world  of  appearance,  which 
gives  Xenophanes  his  place    in  the   history  of   philoso- 
phy.    Otherwise   he   would  have  been  no  more  than   a 
religious  reformer.     As  it  was,  the  religious  element  in  the 
teachings  of  Xenophanes  remained  almost  still-born.    The 
philosophical  alone  has  left  a  mark  on  history. 

Parmenides. 

Parmenides,  of  Elea,  probably  a  pupil  of  Xenophanes 
in  his  old  age,  and  much  esteemed  in  his  native  city  for 

*  "  There  is  one  God  alone,  the  greatest  among  gods  and  men,  resem- 
bling mortals  neither  in  body  nor  in  thought."  Apud  Clem.  Alex,  i.  I. 

J) 


32  GKEEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. 

In  the  Pand  statesmanship,  embodied  his  philosophy  in 
into  ten  sp!?^  C)f  which  considerable  fragments  remain, 
the  central'^esides  an  introduction,  of  two  main  divisions, 
ess'  Jttrbo'  treating  of  the  doctrine  of  the  true,  and  the 
-r.cond  containing  a  cosmical  theory  of  illusory  appearance. 
In  Parmenides,  the  theological  terminology  of  Xeno- 
phanes  is  abandoned.  Being,  as  distinguished  from 
Xon-being,  is  the  subject-matter  of  philosophy.  True 
knowledge,  the  knowledge  of  Being,  is  only  to  be 
obtained  through  intellect ;  the  senses  serve  only  to  delude 
us  with  an  apparent  reality,  which  is  in  truth  non-existent. 
Being  is  one,  unchangeable,  unbecome,  infinite,  and  eternal. 
The  appearance  of  change,  multiplicity,  limitation,  etc., 
in  the  sense  world,  is  illusory.  Parmenides  enunciated 
for  the  first  time,  in  history,  the  doctrine  of  abstract 
Monism,  and  an  abstract  Monism  it  is,  of  the  crudest 
and  most  uncompromising  description. 

Melissos  and  Zeno. 

The  distinguished  Samian  General  Melissos,  also  be- 
longs to  the  Eleatic  school.  His  subject-matter  is  the 
Ens,  or  being,  which,  like  Parmenides,  he  regarded  as 
an  immovable,  indivisible  unity.  Like  Parmenides, 
Melissos  has  a  polemic  against  the  conception  of  a  void, 
which  is  declared  impossible.  His  work  is  mainly 
directed  against  the  Ionian  Physicists. 

The  Eleatic  Zeno  is  stated  to  have  been  an  adopted 
son  of  Parmenides,  whose  doctrines  he  embraced  in  their 
entirety.  He  was  regarded  as  a  man  of  heroic  character, 
and  numerous  stories  of  his  fortitude  are  related.  There 
is  no  new  doctrine  taught  by  Zeno.  His  philosophical 
work  consisted  of  an  attempt  to  fortify  the  positions  of 
Parmenides,  and  to  clinch  his  arguments  and  demonstra- 
tions. This  he  efiected  or  sought  to  efi'ect  b}^  means  of 
Dialectic,  or  the  reductio  ad  ahsurdum,  a  method  of  proof 
which  he  was  the  first  to  employ.  Numerous  instances 
illustrative  of  his  skill  in  this  kind  of  argumentation  are 
transmitted,  of  which  the  most  noted  is  the  so-called 
Achilles-puzzle.  The  object  was  to  prove  the  impossibility 
of  motion.     If  Achilles  and  the  tortoise  run  a  race,  and 


Epoch  L]  THE   PRE-SOKRATIC   SCHOOLS.  35 

Achilles  do  but  give  the  tortoise  a  start,  however  slight, 
he  will  never  overtake  the  tortoise. — Proof  as  follows  :  If 
Achilles  is  to  overtake  the  tortoise,  he  must  first  reach 
the  point  where  the  tortoise  was  when  he  started ;  next 
the  point  it  has  attained  in  the  interval ;  next  the  point 
arrived  at,  while  he  is  making  this  second  advance  ;  and  so 
on  ad  infinitum,  which  is  obviously  impossible  in  a  finite 
time.* 

This  is  one  of  four  arguments  employed  by  Zeno  to 
prove  the  impossibility  of  motion.  Arguments  of  an 
analogous  kind  are  brought  forward  to  demonstrate  the 
impossibility  of  plurality.  In  Zeno  the  opposition  of  the 
Eleatic  philosophy  to  common  sense  is  brought  out  into 
the  most  prominent  relief.  Multiplicity  and  motion  are 
not  encountered  with  general  arguments,  as  with  Par- 
menides,  but  their  impossibility  is  sought  to  be  drawn 
from  their  very  conception.  In  this  way  Zeno's  dialectic 
started  problems  which  philosophy  has  never  since  been 
able  to  evade. 

Soon  after  Melissos  and  Zeno,  the  Eleatic  school  seems 
to  have  died  out,  its  dialectic  being  absorbed  by  the 
Sophists.  It  should  be  observed  that  several  of  the 
Eleatics  included  a  cosmology  (not  very  consistently 
perhaps)  in  their  philosophy,  of  which,  since  it  is  destitute 
of  value  or  importance,  either  intrinsically  or  as  bearing 
on  the  system  proper,  no  account  has  been  given.  One 
point  only  is  worthy  of  notice,  namely,  that  the  Eleatics 
invariably  assumed  two  elements  as  primal  instead  of  the 
one  element  of  the  Ionian  Hylozoists.  In  this  we  may 
perhaps  see  a  transition  to  the  four  elements  of  Empedokles. 
The  way  in  which  the  Eleatic  system,  starting  from  a 
polemic  in  the  person  of  the  founder  against  the  current 
theology,  became  purely  philosophic,  has  already  been 
noticed. 

*  "  The  infinity  of  space  in  this  race  of  subdivision  is  artfully  run 
against  a  finite  time ;  whereas  if  the  one  infinite  were  pitted,  as  m 
reason  it  ought  to  be,  against  the  other  infinite,  the  endless  divisibi- 
lity of  time  against  the  endless  divisibility  of  space,  there  would  arise  a 
reciprocal  exhaustion  and  neutralisation  that  would  swallow  up  the 
astounding  consequences,  very  much  as  the  two  Kilkenny  cats  ate  up 
each  other."    De  Quincey"s  works,  Vol.  XVI.,  p.  154. 

D  2 


36  GEEEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. 


THE  METAPHYSICAL-PHYSICISTS. 


Herakleitos. 

We  have  now  reached  a  group  of  thinkers  who  com- 
bined the  Hylozoism  of  the  lonians  with  the  metaphysical 
methods  of  the  Pythagoreans  and  Xenophanes.*  The 
metaphysic  of  the  Eleatics  was  purely  abstract.  It 
admitted  of  no  modus  vivendi  with  the  material  world. 
One  unchangeable,  immovable  and  eternal  being  alone 
existed  as  the  essence  of  the  real,  all  else  was  absolute 
illusion.  The  negation  of  the  possibility  of  motion  and 
change  was  now  met  by  their  affirmation  as  the  insejDarable 
attribute  of  real  being.  Physics,  or  cosmology,  ceasing  to 
be  separated  by  an  impassable  gulf  from  philosoj^hy 
proper,  as  with  the  Eleatics,  was  absorbed  into  its  central 
doctrine.  The  leading  names  in  this  group  are  Herakleitos, 
Anaxagoras,  Empedocles,  and  Leukippus  and  Demokritos. 

Herakleitos  sprang  from  an  ancient  family  of  Ephesus, 
claiming  descent  from  the  Homeric  Nestor.  He  was  an 
arch-aristocrat,  and  a  bitter  hater  of  the  democracy  of  his 
native  town.  The  date  of  his  birth  was  probably  about 
B.C.  532.  On  account  of  the  mystical  language  in  which 
his  doctrines  were  couched,  he  obtained  the  cognomen  of 
the  "  Obscure." 

The  cardinal  doctrine  of  Herakleitos :  "  All  things 
flow,"  was  an  aphorism  for  the  great  principle  of 
"  becoming ;  "  of  the  identity  in  contradiction  of  all  things, 
which  it  is  the  undoubted  glory  of  the  Ephesian 
thinker  to  have  for  the  first  time  definitely  enunciated. 
Everything  is  and  is  not  at  the  same  moment ;  it  exists 
only  in  transition.  The  inherent  opposition  of  all 
things,  the  strain  of  contradiction  running  through  them, 
he  describes  as  "  the  harmony  of  the  world  like  that  of 
the  lyre  and  the  bow." 

PhysicalJy  expressed,  the  ultimate  essence  of  the  real 

*  The  work  of  Parmenides  was  subsequent  to  that  of  Herakleitos. 


Epoch  I.]  THE   METAPHYSICAL-PHYSICISTS.  37 

was  "  fire,"  that  element  beiug  symbolical  of  non- 
stability,  of  ceaseless  change.  "The  one  world  of  all 
things,  has  not  been  made  either  by  a  god  or  a  man ; 
but  it  was,  and  is,  and  will  be,  an  everliving  fire,  kindling 
itself  according  to  measure  and  extinguisshing  itself 
according  to  measure."  From  the  upper  regions  where 
the  fire  was  purest  it  descended  to  the  middle  regions 
where  it  became  water,  less  pure,  less  living ;  till  finally 
it  reached  the  lowest  region  of  all,  the  region  of  least 
life,  least  change,  and  least  motion,  viz.  the  earth.  At 
this  point  the  reverse  process  commenced,  the  fire 
gradually  ascending  to  the  sphere  of  its  original  purity. 
From  fire  all  things  come,  and  into  fire  they  must 
return.  The  "fire"  of  Herakleitos  must  be  understood 
rather  as  an  incandescent  vapour  than  as  actual  flame. 
The  processes  of  the  evolution  and  dissolution  of  the 
world  out  of  and  into  this  fiery  vaj^our  are  eternally 
alternating. 

Herakleitos  employed  various  illustrations  to  bring 
home  to  the  mind  the  eternal  flux  of  things ;  as  that  one 
could  not  step  twice  into  the  same  river,  etc.  To 
illustrate  that  everything  existed  in  combination  with  its 
opposite,  he  instanced  sleep  and  waking,  life  and  death, 
youth  and  age. 

It  is  a  manifest  historical  misapprehension  to  describe 
Herakleitos,  as  is  done  byUeberweg,  as  a  "  Hylozoist  to  the 
backbone,"  *  since  the  slightest  acquaintance  with  his 
doctrines  suffices  to  show  us  that  their  salient  point  is 
not  so  much  the  theory  of  a  primitive  fire,  which  is  rather 
inferential  and  illustrative,  as  the  doctrine  of  the  eternal 
flux  and  reflux  of  things,  and  of  contradiction  and  strife 
as  essential  to  existence. 

The  Herakleitan  school  continued  to  possess  numerous 
adherents,  especially  in  Ephesus  and  the  Greek  cities  of 
Asia  Minor,  till  the  time  of  Sokrates.  One  of  Plato's 
teachers,  Kratylos,  was  an  Herakleitan. 

The  work  of  Herakleitos  which  bore  the  title,  common 
to  most  of  the  pre-Sokratic  treatises,  Trept  </)i;o-ea>s,  was 
extant  and  much  read  by  the  Christians  of  the  second  and 

*  "  Vom  hause  aus  Hylozoist,"  Ueberweg,  Vol.  I.,  p.  46. 


38  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. 

third  centuries, — but  fragments  only  have  reached  modem 
times. 

There  are  several  monographs  on  Herakleitos,  by 
different  Gi-erman  scholars,  the  most  celebrated  being 
Ferdinand  Lassalle's  great  work.  Die  PJiilosophie  Hera- 
Jcleitos'  des  Dimkeln  von  Epliesos,  2  Bde.^  Berlin,  1858,  the 
critical  value  of  which,  however,  is  impaired  by  its  strong 
Hegelian  tendency. 

EmI'EDOKLES. 

Empedokles  was  born  at  Akragas,  in  Sicily,  B.C.  490. 
His  history  is  overlaid  with  legends,  of  which  the  well- 
known  storj^  of  his  suicide  on  Mount  Etna  is  a  specimen. 
Empedokles,  like  Parmenides,  embodied  his  philosophical 
views  in  an  epic  poem. 

The  four  elements  (so-called),  fire,  water,  earth  and  air,* 
were  to  Empedokles  the  ultimate  forms  of  the  real,  but 
they  were  not  like  the  Ionic  primitive  substance  capable 
of  qualitative  change.  All  things  were  composed  of  these 
four  elements,  but  by  a  mixture  in  various  proportions. 
In  themselves  they  were  absolutely  statical,  possessing  no 
inherent  principle  of  determination,  such  as  condensation 
and  rarefaction,  as  with  the  Hj-lozoists  and  Herakleitos. 
The  change  and  multiplicity  of  things  is  brought  about 
by  mechanical  principles  foreign  to  their  essential  nature. 
Those  principles  were  love  and  hate,  a  uniting  and  a 
separating  principle.  By  this  dualistic  conception  Em- 
pedokles found  the  modus  vivendi  between  the  Absolute 
Being  of  Parmenides,  which  excluded  all  becoming,  and 
therefore  all  reality,  and  the  absolute  flux  of  Herakleitos, 
which  seemed  to  exclude  all  self-existent  Being. 

Empedokles  conceived  of  absolute  existence,  like  Xeno- 
phanes,  as  originally  one  unchanging  all-encompassing 
sphere,  which  the  opposing  influences  of  love  and  hate 
first  reduced  to  the  world  of  change,  motion,  and  plurality 
by  the  comlDination  and  separation  of  the  four  "  roots," 
as  Empedokles  terms  them,  which  it  implicitly  contained. 
Each  of  the  two  forces  prevails  alternately  in  the  process 

*  We  perliaps  ought  rathar  to  say,  the  solid,  the  liquid,  the  gaseous, 
and  the  ethereal,  i.e.  the  four  forms  of  matter. 


Epoch  I.]  THE   METAPHYSICAL-PHYSICISTS.  39 

of  the  world-formation.  Originally,  absolute  love  (i.e. 
union)  obtained.  Hate  gained  an  entrance  and  severed 
the  elements  from  one  another,  in  which  way  individual 
beings  arose.  But  the  power  of  hate  reaching  its  ex- 
tremest  point,  individual  things  cease  to  exist.  Every 
particle  of  matter  is  separated  from  every  other  particle. 
The  combining  influence  of  love  then  enters  again,  and  new 
individual  beings  arise,  till  with  the  complete  re-establish- 
ment of  the  power  of  love  all  reverts  to  the  primal  state 
of  absolute  quiescence  and  unity. 

Empedokles'  philosophy  also  contained  a  theory  of  the 
order  in  time  and  the  manner  of  the  origin  of  plants  and 
animals.  Sense-perception  it  explained  by  the  out-flow- 
ing of  particles  from  external  bodies,  and  their  impinge- 
ment upon  the  organs  of  sense,  every  element  in  bodies 
being  perceived  by  us  through  a  corresponding  element 
in  ourselves. 

Anaxagoras. 

Anaxagoras,  who  was  born  at  Klazomenoe  about  B.C.  500, 
of  a  noble  family,  subsequently  migrated  to  Athens,  and 
became  the  friend  of  Perikles.  Owing  to  an  accusation  of 
atheism,  he  was  compelled  to  leave  the  city,  and  fly  to 
Lampsakos,  where  he  died  at  the  age  of  seventy-two. 

Like  Empedokles  and  the  Atomists,  Anaxagoras  postula- 
ted qualitatively  unchangeable  substance,  by  the  combina- 
tion and  separation  of  which,  individual  things  arose.  This 
substance  consisted  of  an  infinite  interpenetration  of  ele- 
ments, an  infinite  chaos.  It  was  neither  increased  nor 
diminished,  but  suffered  only  combination  and  resolution 
into  infinitely  varying  forms.  The  primitive  aggregate 
was  termed  by  subsequent  exponents  of  the  system  Homoi- 
omeroi.  The  union  of  these  ultimate  elements  with  each 
other  was  so  complete,  that  they  were  divisible  to  infinity, 
there  being  no  ultimate  and  irresolvable  atoms  at  their 
basis.  This  formless  mass  was  subjected  not  to  a  necessary 
law,  but  to  vovs,  or  mind,  an  omnipotent  and  omniscient 
power  that  produced  order  and  harmony  out  of  the  chaos. 
The  separation  is  conceived  as  going  out  successively  from 
a  middle  point  in  ever-widening  circles.  As  with  most  of 
the  ancients,  Anaxagoras  regarded  the  earth  as  the  centre 


40  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. 

of  the  universe.     His  theory  of  the  origin  of  organic  beings 
strongly  resembled  that  of  Anaximandros. 

The  two  most  noteworthy  points  in  the  philosophy  of 
Anaxagoras  are  the  introduction  of  the  notion  of  mind  into 
philosophic  speculation,  and  the  assertion  of  the  infinite 
divisibility  of  matter,  or,  as  it  is  termed,  Dynamism.  A 
great  deal  has  been  made  of  the  first  of  these  points,  as 
might  naturally  be  expected,  but  so  far  from  its  supposing 
any  advance  in  conception,  we  may  rather  consider  it  as 
philosophically  a  reaction  to  anthropomorphism.  The 
appearance  of  the  problem  of  the  ultimate  constitution 
of  matter  upon  the  arena  of  speculation,  on  the  other 
hand,  undoubtedly  marks  an  epoch  in  the  history  of 
thought,  and  had  immediate  results. 

The  Atomists. 

The  reputed  founder  of  Atomism  in  Greece  was  Leu- 
kippus,  respecting  whom  scarcely  anything  is  known,  not 
even  whether  he  committed  his  doctrines  to  writing  or 
not.  According  to  Aristotle,  he  originally  belonged  to  the 
Eleatic  school.  The  real  literary  founder  of  the  school, 
Demokritos,  who  is  described  as  a  pupil  of  Leukippus, 
flourished  about  half  a  century  later  than  Anaxagoras. 
He  was  born  at  Abdera,  and  is  stated  to  have  employed 
the  large  fortune  he  possessed  in  travelling  throughout 
Egypt  and  the  East.  He  died  at  an  advanced  age,  much 
respected,  in  his  native  town.  Demokritos  composed  a 
large  number  of  works,  all  of  which,  with  the  exception  of 
fragments  preserved  by  later  writers,  have  perished. 

The  Atomistic  system  connects  itself  by  opposition,  in 
an  unmistakable  manner,  with  that  of  Anaxagoras.  The 
latter  philosopher  had  assumed  a  chaotic  aggregate  divis- 
ible to  infinity  as  the  primal  substance  of  all  things. 
Demokritos  postulates  a  plenum  and  a  void,  the  former 
of  which  he  also  terms  existent,  and  the  latter  non- 
existent. The  existent  consists  of  an  infinite  plurality 
of  atoms,  each  of  which  is  indivisible.  Between  the 
atoms  is  the  void  or  non-existent.  The  connection  and 
distinction  between  this  system  and  that  of  Anaxagoras  is 
obvious.     AVith  Anaxagoras  the  plenum  was  practically  a 


Epoch  I.]  THE   METAPHYSICAL-PHYSICISTS.  41 

continuous  substance,  for  the  plural  designation  can  only- 
have  a  qualitative  application,  the  notion  of  the  "  void  "  or 
empty  space  being  excluded.  The  atoms  of  Demokritos,  on 
the  contrary,  were  conditioned  in  their  existence  by  the 
void,  in  other  words  they  were  discrete  substances.  The 
Homoiomerioi  of  Anaxagoras,  again,  were  infinitely  divisible, 
the  atoms  of  Demokritos  absolutely  indivisible. 

The  action  of  the  atoms  was  conditioned  in  a  triple  way, 
by  their  order,  their  position  and  th.Q\r  form.  Their  size  was 
various,  but  upon  it  depended  their  weight,  that  is,  their 
tendency  to  move  do^vnwards.  The  atoms,  like  the  void, 
w^ere  eternal.  Their  motion  was  also  original  and  eternal. 
The  weight  of  the  atoms  being  unequal,  some  falling  with 
a  greater  velocity  than  others,  gave  rise,  according  to 
Demokritos,  to  lateral  motions,  which  again  with  the 
original  motion,  constituted  a  circular  or  vortex  motion, 
which  was  ever  extending  itself,  and  w^hich  was  the 
proximate  cause  of  the  world-formation.  In  this  theory, 
we  have  a  distinct  reminiscence  of  Anaxagoras.  These 
positions,  the  Atomists  thought,  sufficed  to  explain  the 
variety  of  phenomena. 

The  suj)er-sensible  atoms  and  the  void  alone  existed  in 
themselves,  the  real  world  existed  for  us  only.  Perception 
was  explained  by  the  efflux  of  atoms  from  bodies  producing 
images  on  our  mind  through  the  medium  of  the  organs 
of  sense.  Demokritos  was  the  last  of  the  Metaphysical- 
Physicists,  and  of  the  older  Greek  speculators.  The 
crisis  produced  by  the  Sophists  had  already  begun ;  the 
attention  of  philosophy  was  already  being  drawn  away 
from  the  contemplation  of  Being  to  Knowing,  from  the 
object  to  the  subject,  and  Greek  thought  was  fast  becoming 
ripe  for  the  magical  and  renovating  touch  of  Demokritos^^ 
younger  contemporary  Sokrates. 


42  »  GEEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.      ^ 

TRANSITION  TO  SOKRATES. 

The  Sophists. 

The  founder  of  tlie  negative  and  sceptical  school  of  the 
Sophists  or  "wise  men"  is  usually  designated  as  Protagoras. 
This  brilliant  philosophical  free-lance  wasbomat  Abdera,  the 
city  of  Demokritos,  in  a  humble  sphere  of  life,  out  of  which 
his  abilities  soon  carried  him.  After  travelling  in  Sicily, 
he  settled  at  Athens,  where  he  made  much  money  and 
fame  by  his,  teaching,  for  which  he  was  the  first  to  demand 
payment.  Led,  it  is  stated,  by  the  Herakleitan  doctrines 
to  a  sceptical  attitude,  his  fundamental  thesis  gradually 
acquired  shape.  It  consisted,  to  put  it  in  modern 
language,  in  the  denial  of  all  objectivity  and  the 
restriction  of  all  knowledge  to  mere  impressions  of  the 
individual  subject.  Protagoras  maintained  that  to  every 
assertion  a  contrary  assertion  could  be  opposed  with  equal 
right.  His  favourite  aphorism  was :  "  Man  is  the  measure 
of  all  things."  As  a  result,  probability  took  the  place  of 
truth,  and  immediate  utility,  of  goodness. 

Prodikos,  born  in  the  island  of  Chios,  also  came  to 
Athens  while  a  young  man,  and  adopted  the  calling  of 
Sophist.  His  chief  merit  lies  in  his  having  contributed  to 
fix  the  definitions  of  words,  thus  preparing  the  way  for 
the  Sokratic  dialectic.  His  lectures  were  so  much  in 
request  as  to  enable  him  to  make  a  charge  of  fifty 
drachmas  a  person. 

Another  eminent  name  in  the  Sophist  school  was 
(rorgias,  who,  evidently  influenced  by  the  Eleatics, 
maintained  that  neither  being  or  non-being,  one  or  many, 
become  or  unbecome,  had  any  reality  or  meaning.  His 
orations,  in  which  a  similar  dialectical  mode  of  argument 
to  that  of  Zeno  was  employed,  were  delivered  publicly 
on  any  given  subject.  Extemporaneous  oratory  and 
oral  disputation  he  attached  much  importance  to,  and 
became  eminent  throughout  Greece  and  the  colonies 
for  his  skill  in  these  arts.  Two  orations,  of  doubtful 
genuineness,  have    come   down   to   us   under   his   name. 


Epoch  L]  THE   SOKKATIC   SCHOOLS.  43 

Among  other  eminent  Sophists  may  be  mentioned 
Hippias,  Polos,  Thrasymachos,  etc. 

The  Sophists  practically  dealt  a  death-blow  at  the 
earlier  philosophies  considered  as  independent  systems,  by 
opposing  them  to  each  other  and  showing  the  one-sided- 
ness  of  each,  while  the  plausibility  of  the  several  doctrines 
taken  by  themselves,  combined  with  their  mutually 
exclusive  character  to  produce  a  spirit  of  universal 
scepticism  throughout  the  philosophic  world,  even  apart 
from  the  arguments  more  especially  directed  to  this  end. 
The  individualist  and  utilitarian  nature  of  the  Sophistic 
ethics  naturally  procured  for  the  doctrine  wide  accepta- 
tion at  a  time  when  the  old  civic  feeling  was  beginning  to 
wane.  The  "  gilded  youth  "  of  the  Greek  cities  flocked  to 
the  lectures  of  its  professors,  more  to  learn  the  art  of 
skilful  disputation,  for  the  profitable  exercise  of  which 
the  public  life  of  the  Hellenic  race  afforded  such  a  wide 
field  at  this  period,  than  from  any  intrinsic  interest  in 
philosophical  questions.  As  a  natural  consequence,  the 
whole  Sophistic  teaching  ultimately  came  to  have  mere 
rhetorical  display  for  its  end,  by  which  those  proficient 
therein  might  make  the  worse  appear  the  better  reason,  as 
occasion  required. 

It  was  this  empty  dialectical  art  that  reigned  almost 
supreme  in  Greece  under  the  name  of  philosophy,  when  the 
"  Silenus  figure  "  appeared  in  the  Agora  at  Athens,  with 
a  dialectic  similar  indeed  in  kind,  but  employed  for 
another  purpose ;  a  dialectic  which  was  destined  to  make 
an  end  of  Sophism,  as  Sophism  had  made  an  end  of  pre- 
vious dogmatism.  It  has  been  often  remarked,  and  with 
justice,  that  the  Sophistic  movement  was  never  strictly 
philosophical,  but  was  rather  a  popular  rationalistic  out- 
burst, having  its  springs  in  the  entire  religious,  political 
and  social  life  of  Greece  shortly  before  the  Peloponnesian 
war.  As  such  it  is  difficult  to  fix  upon  any  individual  as 
the  acti^al  founder  of  the  movement,  which,  so  far  as  names 
are  concerned,  was  rather  consentaneous  than  successive. 
The  sudden  appearance  of  the  Sophistic  orators  throughout 
Xhe  Greek  world  is  one  of  those  phenomena  in  the  history 
of  culture,  for  which  not  more  than  general  causes  can  be 
assigned  in  the  absence  of  exhaustive  historical  data. 


44  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

SECOND  EPOCH. 

SOKEATES. 

We  have  now  arrived  at  the  first  great  land- mark 
in  Greek  speculation.  The  personality  of  the  son  of 
Sophroniskos  is  one  of  the  few  world-personalities  whose 
name  and  fame  have  found  an  echo  amid  all  races,  where- 
ever  human  culture  has  existed. 

The  date  of  Sokrates'  birth  is  approximately  fixed  at 
from  B.  c.  471  to  469.  He  was  the  first  philosopher  born 
in  Athens,  where  his  father  was  a  sculptor,  a  calling  he 
himself  followed  during  the  early  portion  of  his  career. 
After  receiving  the  education  prescribed  by  law,  Sokrates 
appears  to  have  taken  up  the  studies  of  astronomy  and 
geometry.  The  story  of  his  having  been  a  pupil  of 
Anaxagoras  or  Archelaus,  is  generally  regarded  as  a 
fabrication,  though  there  is  no  doubt  that  he  attended 
the  lectures  of  the  Sophists,  notably  Prodikos.  It  is  also 
probable  that  he  read  most  of  the  extant  philosophical 
literature  ;  he  was  certainly  familiar  with  the  treatise  of 
Anaxagoras.  Plato  relates  that  he  came  personally  into 
contact  with  Parmenides  while  a  boy — a  statement  which 
Ueberweg  credits,  though  generally  considered  doubtful. 

Sokrates  took  part  in  three  campaigns  during  the 
Peloponnesian  war,  in  which  he  signalised  himself  by  his 
courage  and  endurance.  Otherwise  he  held  aloof  from 
public  aftairs,  onty  once  in  his  life  occupying  an  official 
position.  Seldom  leaving  his  beloved  Athens,  he  daily 
mixed  with  the  crowds  that  thronged  the  Agora,  willing 
to  converse  with  all  who  wished  to  do  so.  Young  men 
were  especially  attracted  by  him,  and  presently  the  world- 
famous  group,  comprising  among  others,  Plato,  Xenophon, 
Eschines,  Euripides,  Krito,  etc.,  came  to  be  formed. 
Meanwhile,  Sokrates  had  acquired  a  celebrity  which 
eclipsed  that  of  his  Sophist  teachers,  and  which  led  the 
comic  poet  Aristophanes,  who  hated  philosophy,  to  satirise 
it  in  his  person  in  the '  Clouds.'  It  is  a  noticeable  fact  that 
Aristophanes  apj^ears  to  have  been  about  as  ignorant  of 


Epoch  II.]  SOKRATES.  45 

the  tiling  he  was  satirising  as  many  popular  writers  in 
our  own  day,  who,  without  his  genius,  attempt  to  make 
fun  of  new  truths  and  their  advocates,  for,  like  them,  he 
seemed  to  consider  it  immaterial,  so  long  as  he  was 
attacking  philosophy,  what  distinctions  of  stand-point  he 
confounded.  Thus  Sokrates  is  represented  in  the  character 
of  a  Sophist,  Aristophanes  being  apparently  oblivious  of 
the  fact  that  Sokrates  led  a  polemic  against  the  Sophists. 

The  main,  and  we  may  perhaps  say,  only,  thesis  in 
Sokrates'  philosophy  was  the  assertion  of  the  identity  of 
knowledge  and  virtue.  No  man  was  willingly  bad,  but 
only  from  ignorance  and  confusion.  As  a  corollary  from 
this  we  have  the  assumption  that  virtue  is  teachable,  and 
that  as  all  knowledge  is  essentially  one,  so  is  virtue.  The 
revolution  effected  by  Sokrates  has  been  well  described  by 
Cicero  as  consisting  in  the  bringing  down  of  philosophy 
from  heaven  to  earth.  Had  Sokrates  written  a  treatise,  it 
would  not  have  borne  the  traditional  title  of  those  of  his 
predecessors,  "  On  Nature,"  but  rather  "  On  Man."  The 
immediate  object  of  his  teaching  was  the  attainment  of  clear 
ideas  or  concepts,  the  highest  of  all  being  that  of  the  good, 
or  the  Summum  Bonum ;  in  order  through  this  knowledge 
to  attain  the  perfect  life.  Eeferring  to  his  mother,  the 
midwife  Phanarete,  he  used  to  say  that  as  her  calling  in  life 
was  to  deliver  children  into  the  world  from  the  womb,  so  it 
was  his  calling  to  watch  over  mental  parturition,  and  deliver 
ideas  from  the  mind.  The  method  he  used  to  effect  this, 
was  that  of  irony,  or  pretended  ignorance.  He  would  ask 
questions  on  any  subject,  as  though  for  information.  The 
oftentimes  confident  answers  received  would  lead  to 
further  questions,  till  in  the  end  the  luckless  victim  of 
confused  ideas  and  loose  thought,  would  be  brought  to 
silence,  if  not  to  an  admission  of  the  victory  of  the  Sokratic 
dialectic.  Aristotle  declares  Sokrates  to  have  been  the 
founder  of  the  inductive  method,  though  this  could  only 
have  been  as  applied  to  ethical  subjects  and  the  defini- 
tion of  words ;  but  here  again  it  would  seem  only  fair  to 
credit  his  master  Prodikos  with  the  foundation  of  this 
logical  art. 

The  Sophists  had  identified  truth  with  individual 
opinion  or  conception.     Sokrates  distinguished   between 


46  GEEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

indivicUial  conceptions  as  such,  and  those  that,  purified  by- 
Dialectic,  were  of  universal  application,  i.e.,  true.  All 
learning  was  recollection  ;  all  teaching  the  bringing  to 
light  and  clearness  of  ideas  already  existing,  although 
confusedly,  in  the  mind  of  the  taught.  The  result  of 
Sokrates'  Dialectic  was  often  simply  to  demonstrate  the 
reciprocal  untenability  of  rival  theories,  without  reaching 
any  positive  conclusion.  Much  has  been  written  respect- 
ing the  Scu/i-oi'tov  of  Sokrates.  There  seems  every  reason 
for  thinking  that  in  accordance  with  the  prevalent  beliefs 
he  really  regarded  himself  as  under  the  supervision  of  a 
tutelary  supernatural  agent,  which  warned  him  of  the 
danger  attending  certain  courses  of  action. 

The  story  of  Sokrates'  condemnation  and  death  is  too  well 
known  to  need  repeating  at  length  in  a  work  of  the  present 
scope.  Having  excited  the  enmity  of  the  pietists,  by  his 
refusal  to  be  initiated  into  the  Eleusinian  mysteries,  and 
the  hostility  of  the  democratic  party  by  his  former  friend- 
ship with  Kritias,  one  of  the  worst  of  the  thirty  tyrants, 
for  which  the  subsequent  breach  between  them  had  not 
atoned ;  also  probably  by  the  fact  of  his  having  remained 
unmolested  in  Athens  throughout  tlie  worst  period  of  the 
tyranny  ;  he  was  impeached  by  JMeletos,  an  inferior  poet, 
Lykon,  a  Khetorician,  and  Anytos,  a  leather-dealer,  on 
three  counts,  charging  him  respectively,  with  "introducing 
strange  Gods,"  with  corrupting  youth,  and  with  having 
moulded  the  character  of  tyrants.  He  was  convicted  and 
condemned  to  death,  at  first  by  a  majority  of  six,  but  subse- 
quently on  appeal,  of  eighty  votes.  The  circumstance  that 
the  sacred  vessel  bearing  the  Athenian  ofierings  had  just 
sailed  for  Delos,  allowed  him  nearly  a  month's  respite — 
during  which  he  refused  the  means  of  escape  ofi'ered  him — 
before,  in  April  B.C.  399,  he  drank  the  hemlock  in  the 
presence  of  his  sorrowing  disciples. 

Much  exaggerated  blame  has  been  bestowed  on  the 
Athenians  for  the  condemnation  of  Sokrates.  There  is 
strong  evidence  that  in  its  early  stages  at  least  he  favoured 
the  Lacedemonian  policy,  while  his  known  intimacy  with 
Kritias  naturally  threw  grave  suspicion  on  bis  teaching. 
As  Thirlwall  remarks,  the  strangeness  consists  not  in  the 
fact  of  the  conviction,  but  in  the  smallness  of  the  majority 


ErocH  II.]  THE   SOKRATIC   SCHOOLS.  47 

by  which  the  philosopher  was  at  first  convicted.  But, 
though  even  the  external  circumstances  of  the  case  are 
sufficient  to  account  for  the  action  of  the  Athenians,  there 
is,  we  believe,  a  deeper  significance  in  the  attitude  of  all 
that  was  conservative  in  the  Athenian  state  towards 
Sokrates.  It  was  not  zeal  for  the  gods,  qua  gods,  as  we 
take  it,  that  formed  the  underlying  ground  of  suspicion, 
but  zeal  for  the  old  civic  spirit.  The  citizens  of  Athens 
felt  vaguely  that  the  "  Know  thyself"  of  Sokrates  was  the 
expression  of  a  religion  and  an  ethic,  radically  incom- 
patible with  the  old  spirit  of  solidaritj^ — an  ethic  of 
individualism  and  introspection,  which,  if  j^nshed  to  its 
logical  conclusions,  must  sap  the  ancient  traditional  ethic 
of  duty  to  the  state  as  an  organised  whole  at  its  very  root. 
This  introspection  was  the  "  strange  god  "  of  which  the 
Athenians  felt  an  uneasy  dread,  as  destructive  of  the  old 
state  religion  and  morality.  It  is  somewhat  of  an  irony  on 
the  almost  servile  respect  with  which  Sokrates  generally 
treated  the  established  cultus,  and  his  excessive  care  to 
avoid  any  imputation  of  impiety,  that  this  should  have 
constituted  one  (jf  the  main  charges  against  him  in  the 
capital  indictment. 

The  revolution  in  thought  inaugurated  by  Sokrates  con- 
sisted, (I.),  in  the  retrospective  method  he  employed,  the 
change  in  thesubject-matter  of  philosophy,  from  things  to 
ideas,  from  being  to  knowing,  and  (II.),  in  the  ethical  and 
individualist  tendency  of  all  his  work.  Henceforward 
ethics,  and  the  ethical  sciences,  occupy,  if  not  as  with 
Sokrates,  an  exclusive,  at  least  a  foremost,  place  in  every 
system. 

The  Sokratic  Schools. 

In  the  nature  of  the  case,  it  was  impossible  for  Sokrates 
to  leave  behind  him  a  school  of  pure  Sokratists.  His 
philosophy  was  rather  a  mfethod  than  a  doctrine.  Sokrates 
had  said  that  the  only  sense  in  which  he  could  interpret 
the  Delphic  oracle's  words,  that  he  was  the  wisest  man  in 
Greece,  was,  that  while  others  thought  they  knew  some- 
thing, he  knew  that  he  knew  nothing,  and  thus  in  his 
person  fulfilled  the  Delphic  maxim  "Know  thyself." 
Thus  the  Sokratic  method  of  philosophy,  of  the  search  after 


48  GKEEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

clear  ideas  and  virtue,  or  the  "  perfect  life,"  was  pursued  in 
various  directions,  and  led  with  diiferent  temperaments 
to  different  results  ;  for  all  of  which,  however,  it  was 
possible  to  find  some  justification  in  the  many-sided 
utterances  of  the  master.  There  were  naturally,  among 
the  disciples  of  Sokrates,  personalities,  like  Xenophon, 
mere  men  of  the  world,  who  had  been  generally  influenced 
and  attracted  by  the  conversation  of  Sokrates,  but  had  no 
independent  interest  in  philosophy. 

On  the  other  hand,  there  were  those  who  had  a  real 
interest  in  the  philosophical  side  of  Sokrates,  who  sought 
to  derive  some  definite  result  from  the  life  and  teaching 
of  their  master,  to  formulate  for  themselves  and  their 
followers  what  his  aims  were,  and  what  his  teaching 
really  led  to,  when  logically  carried  out. 

These  were  the  founders  of  the  minor  or  "  imperfect " 
(because  one-sided)  Sokratic  schools,  as  they  are  termed, 
of  which  there  are  three,  the  Megaric,  the  Cyrenaic  and 
the     Cynic.      The    originator    of   the   first  of  these   was 
Euklid,    of    Megara.     Before   he  became    a    disciple    of 
Sokrates,  Euklid  had  embraced  the  Eleatic  philosophy  ^ 
which  he  never   subsequently   abandoned,   interweavir.    ' 
the  Sokratic   Ethics   in   an   ingenious  manner  witn   txa' 
One-Being  doctrine  of  Parmenides.     As  with  Sokrates,  th 
proper  subject-matter  of  philosophy  was  the  Good  ;  br 
Euklid  identified  this  ideal  Good    of  Sokrates  with  t^ 
ontological  One  of  the  Eleatics.     To  him  virtue,  kno 
ledge,  God,  &c.,  were  only  diverse  names  for  this  absolu 
fact.     There   was   certainly   little   more    than    a   formal 
carrying  out  of  the  Sokratic  doctrine  in  Euklid's  system, 
since  Ethics,  jjer  se,   appear  to  have  been  neglected  by 
him  and  his  school,  whose  main  interest  centred  in  dia- 
lectical polemic,  after  the  manner  of  Zeno. 

Aristippus,  the  founder  of  the  Cyrenaic  school,  was  the 
son  of  a  wealthy  merchant  of  the  gay  and  voluptuous  city  of 
Gyrene.  Attracted  by  the  fame  of  Sokrates,  he  came  to 
Athens,  and  remained  in  close  intimacy  with  him  till  his 
death.  Aristij^pus  was  much  more  of  a  Sokratist  than 
Euklid.  He  despised  all  speculation  not  having  an 
immediate  bearing  on  practice.  The  life  of  man  alone 
had  an  interest  for  him.     He   diverged,  however,  from 


Epoch  II.]  THE   SOKKATIC   SCHOOLS.  49 

Sokrates  on  the  opposite  side  to  Euklid,  in  the  vahie  lie 
ulaced  on  Dialectics  and  reasoning  generally  ;  maintaining 
.hat  all  knowledge  was  in  essence  merely  that  o^  our  own 
individual  states  of  feeling.  Hence  the  consideration  of 
these  and  their  causes  make  up  the  whole  subject-matter 
of  the  theoretical  side  of  his  philosophy.  All  states 
of  consciousness  are  reducible  to  violent  motion,  moderate 
motion,  and  the  lack  of  all  motion.  The  first  is  jDain,  the 
second  is  pleasure,  and  the  third  is  apathy.  Pleasure, 
Aristippus  boldly  proclaimed  as  the  only  good.  The 
practical  side  of  philosophy  was  the  attainment  of  pleasure, 
the  great  art  of  life  that  of  avoiding  pain  and  apathy.  With 
Aristippus,  it  was  the  immediate  pleasure  of  the  moment 
that  was  to  be  sought,  and  which  the  "  wise  man  "  was  to 
seize.  He  was  not,  however,  to  be  governed  or  controlled 
by  it,  but,  as  it  were,  to  ride  it,  as  a  horseman  rides  his 
steed.  On  the  other  hand,  the  Cyrenaic  "  wise  man " 
w^ould  not  embrace  a  present  pain  even  with  a  view  to 
future  pleasure. 

It  was  this  point  which  mainly  distinguished  the 
hedonism  of  Aristij^pus  from  that  of  Epicurus,  of  whose 
ethical  system  he  was  otherwise  the  forerunner,  and  in 
whose  school  the  Cyrenaics  became  subsequently  merged. 
Numerous  writings  are  attributed  to  Aristippus,  as  to 
Euklid,  but  they  have  completelj^  perished  in  both  cases. 

The  creator  of  the  Cynic  school,  or  rather  sect,  was  the 
Athenian  Antisthenes,  who,  after  an  education  at  the 
hands  of  Gorgias  the  Sophist,  came  to  Sokrates.  What 
specially  charmed  him  in  the  latter,  was  his  independence 
of  external  "  goods  "  and  what  to  others  were  the  ne- 
cessities of  life ;  his  superhuman  hardihood  in  adversitj'. 
He  subsequently  set  up  as  a  teacher  in  the  gymnasium  of 
the  Kynosarges,  whence  the  name  of  the  sect.  Antis- 
thenes became  enamoured  of  the  notion  of  the  pride  of 
virtue,  upon  which  he  heard  Sokrates  dilate,  and  it  was 
this  that  he  and  his  followers  caricatured  in  their  own 
persons.  With  Antisthenes,  as  with  Sokrates,  virtue 
was  the  one  thing  worth  living  for,  but  his  ideal  virtue 
Antisthenes  placed  in  deprivation  and  asceticism.  Ab- 
solute indifference  to  circumstances  was  the  first  and  the 
last  demand  of  wisdom,  Avhich  stood  in  no  need  of  elabo- 

E 


50  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

rate  argumentation,  but  only  of  strength  of  character. 
Its  sole  end  consisted  in  the  avoidance  of  the  pleasures 
and  desires  that  so  readily  gain  the  mastery  over  us,  and 
a  fortiori  of  all  that  bears  the  impress  of  luxury  or  even 
refinement.  Accordingly  the  Cynics  (of  whom  the  best 
known  is  not  so  much  the  founder  of  the  sj^stem,  as  his 
successor,  the  famous  Diogenes  of  Sinope,  but  whose 
lives  were  all  cast  in  one  mould)  were  content  with  at 
most  a  wallet  and  a  staif,  ate  anything  they  could  obtain, 
slept  in  the  first  place  that  presented  itself,  and  jDcrformed 
all  the  offices  of  life  in  public.  The  Cynics  committed 
nothing  to  writing,  and  all  that  has  been  handed  down 
from  thein  consists  of  j^ersonal  anecdotes,  miscellaneous 
maxims  and,  to  modern  ears,  somewhat  feeble  witticisms. 


Epoch  III.]  PLATO   AND   ARISTOTLE.  51 

THIRD  EPOCH. 

TLATO  AND  AEISTOTLE. 

This  third  epoch  in  Greek  philosophy  is  a  landmark 
not  merely  in  the  history  of  philosophy  but  in  the  history 
of  human  thought  and  culture  generally.  In  these 
two  great  typical  thinkers  the  thought  of  all  preceding- 
ages  converged  as  in  a  focus,  while  from  them  have 
diverged  rays,  which  have  more  or  less  guided  all  later 
inquirers  directly  or  indirectly,  and  influenced  all  the 
more  important  currents  of  thought  in  the  world's  subse- 
quent history.  Plato  and  Aristotle  are  frequently  regarded 
as  antithetic  and  mutually  exclusive ;  they  are  really 
complementary.  Plato  is  occupied  mainly  with  an  inquiry 
as  to  the  necessary  and  universal  element  in  experience. 
Aristotle  supplements  this  inquiry,  by  one  respecting  the 
contingent  and  particular  element  in  the  real,  the  em- 
pirical laws  to  which  special  departments  of  phenomena 
are  subordinated.  In  this  way,  he  became  the  founder  of 
the  inductive  method  of  physical  science.  Before  com- 
mencing o*ur  analysis  of  the  systems  of  Plato  and  Aristotle 
it  will  be  desirable  to  take  a  rapid  survey  of  the  ground 
we  have  been  traversing,  and  which  has  led  up  to  them. 
In  this  way  we  shall  better  be  able  to  judge  what  is 
their  special  individual  contribution  to  human  thought, 
and  what  is  merely  the  welding  together  into  an  organic 
whole  of  the  more  or  less  fragmentary  doctrines  of  their 
predecessors. 

The  Ionian  Physicists  contented  themselves  with  a 
search  after  some  primitive  corporeal  substance.  In  this 
they  implicitly  assumed  unity  as  the  basis  of  the  real 
world.  The  last  important  member  of  the  school, 
Diogenes  of  Apollonia,  explicitly  formulated  the  monistic 
doctrine,  and  endeavoured  to  show  that  the  world  must 
be  so  to  speak  "cut  out  of  one  block,"  that  there  must  he 
one  principle  immanent  in  its  multiplicity.  This,  the 
Pythagoreans  had  already  accentuated  in  their  doctrine 
of  the  Noetic  one,  or  unity,  in  which  all  numbers,  and,  a 

E  2 


52  GEEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

fortiori,  all  tilings  were  immanent.  But  the  Pythagoreans, 
besides  this,  removed  the  inquiry  from  the  ground  of 
concrete  substance  to  that  of  abstract  mathematical 
relations.  These  were  of  course  hypostasized,  and'  made 
the  essences  of  which  the  real  world  was  the  manifesta- 
tion, and  which  were  in  their  turn  the  manifestation  of  the 
original  unity.  Thus  at  the  same  time  that  an  addition 
to  the  range  of  philosophic  inquiry  was  made  by  this 
introduction  of  abstract  notions,  the  monistic  principle 
was  raised  to  an  integral  place  in  philosophy.  The 
Eleatics,  by  pushing  this  principle  to  its  extreme  limits, 
forced  into  relief  the  opposition  of  the  abstract  and  the 
concrete,  the  one  and  the  many,  an  opposition  which 
they  made  absolute. 

They  were  thus  compelled  by  their  fundamental 
principle  to  deny  the  sense-world,  an  issue  which  led  to 
the  introduction  of  a  Dialectic,  based  on  an  examination 
of  its  fundamental  notions.  But  the  one-sided  Monism 
of  the  Southern  Italians  was  encountered  in  Asia  Minor 
by  a  Monism  embodied  in  perhaps  the  most  V..  'liant 
of  all  the  pre-Sokratic  systems,  that  of  Herakleitos.  This 
Monism  took  its  stand  on  the  fusion  of  the  very  contraries 
whose  opposition  the  Eleatics  would  have  made  absolute. 
The  other  philosojjhers  of  the  Metaphy si  c£p1- Physicist 
group  attempted  the  solution  of  the  same  problem — 
namely,  to  tind  a  modus  vivendi  between  abstract  absolute 
Being  and  the  multiplicity  of  the  sense-world — but  they 
failed  to  formulate  anything  satisfactory.  They  all 
sacrificed  the  one  to  the  many  at  starting;  their  systems 
are  pluralistic ;  in  other  words,  the  knot  is  cut  but  not 
untied.  Then  came  the  Sophists,  who  placed  all  these 
various  systems  on  a  level,  by  declaring  man  to  be  the 
measure  of  all  things,  thereby  practically  denying  the 
possibility  of  truth  in  a  higher  sense.  Following  the 
hint  given  by  them,  though  despising  their  pedantry, 
Sokrates  abandoned  the  search  for  physical  or  meta- 
physical truth,  and  applied  himself  to  the  search  for 
logical  truth,  to  the  definition  and  formulation  of  concepts, 
and  the  attainment  of  "  virtue  "  which  necessarily  followed 
from  a  knowledge  of  the  ideal  "  good."  Sokrates  was  em- 
phatically the  philosopher  and  the  apostle  of  inwardness. 


Erocii  III.]  PLATO   AND   ARISTOTLE.  53 

^'Know  thyself/'  was  the  bepjuninpi;  aD(L-_fiJ3iL  of  his 
tgacliiiig!  But  this  self-kno\vleclgo  involved  the  ,  trans- 
formation of  the  confused  and  ha})hazard  thought  of  the 
multitude,  which  the  least  criticism  could  involve  in 
hopeless  contradiction,  into  clear,  well-defined  notions, 
capable  of  universal  application. 

A  development  of  three  hundred  years  thus  culminated 
in  Plato.  Plato  represents  the  synthesis  of  Sokratism  and 
Pre-Sokratism.  In  Plato  the  essence  of  the  whole  pre- 
Sokratic  philosophy  is  to  be  found  transfused  and  trans- 
formed by  the  Dialectic  of  Sokrates.  The  element  which 
is  most  prominent  in  the  constructive  portion  of  his 
Avork  is  Pythagoreanism,  but  he  owes  scarcely  less  a  debt 
TO  the  Eieatics,  to  Herakleitos,  and  even  to  the  sceptical 
theories  of  the  Sophists. 

Aristotle,  while  starting  from  the  synthesis  of  Plato, 
brought  the  power  of  his  mighty  intellect  to  bear  upon 
it  with  the  result  that  he  effected  a  more  complete  fusion 
of  the  pre-Sokratic  thought  than  even  Plato  had  done ; 
that  is,  he  seized  more  completely  the  meaning  and  the 
essential  in  those  systems.  He  more  thoroughly  separated 
the  ore,  which  they  severally  contained,  from  the  accidental 
dross  with  which  it  was  combined.  For  instance,  how 
many  a  clumsily  expressed  doctrine  and  distinction  of 
Pythagorean  and  Eleatic  lay  hidden  under  the  cardinal 
antithesis  of  form  and  matter.  What  a  light  was  cast  on 
the  problems  of  philosophy  by  the  at  once  definite  and  com- 
prehensive expression  (an  expression  covering  neither  too 
much  nor  too  little),  of  a  principle  which  preceding  thinkers 
had  been  vainly  groping  after  in  the  dark,  now  grasping  it 
for  an  instant,  now  blindly  clutching  at  some  other,  quite 
unessential  fact  in  mistake  for  it.  But  Aristotle's  more 
popular,  though  not  greater  title  to  fame,  lay  in  his 
foundation  of  the  inductive  method,  and  of  natural  science 
itself  in  the  modern  sense  of  the  word.  Observation 
arul  P.vpp.rjjmpmj^^  r.ollpr>.t,ir)n^_iiifting  and  COJuparison^of 
facts, ~witli__a_viewL of  through  them  arriving  at  general 
principles,  has  its  origin  in  the  thinker  of  Stagira. 


54  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 


PLATO. 

Plato,  or  to  give  liiin  his  correct  appellation,  Aristokles, 
was  bom  at  Athens  about  B.C.  429,  his  father's  name  being 
Ariston,  and  his  mother's  Periktione.  His  youth  was 
passed  amid  the  artistic  splendours  which  the  age  of 
Perikles  had  left  behind  it.  Born  of  an  aristociatic 
family,  he  hated  the  democracy  of  Athens  no  less  than  his 
master,  Sokrates.  As  a  youth,  he  appears  to  have  occu- 
pied himself  with  poetic  attempts,  which  he  committed  to 
the  flames,  when  in  his  twentieth  j^ear,  he  decided  to 
devote  himself  to  philosophy.  Previously  to  his  acquaint- 
ance with  Sokrates,  which  occurred  at  this  time,  he 
received  instruction  in  philosophy  from  Kratylos  the 
Herakleitan,  and  probably  from  Epicharmos  the  Pytha- 
gorean. He  also  seems  to  have  been  conversant  with  the 
philosophy  of  the  Ionian  school,  as  well  as  with  that  of 
Anaxagoras.  Of  his  long  and  close  intimacy  with  Sokrates, 
in  the  course  of  which  his  own  system  gradually  took 
shape,  it  is  only  necessary  to  make  mention. 

After  the  execution  of  his  master,  he  repaired  to  Megara, 
remaining  some  time  in  companionship  with  Euklid,  doubt- 
less devoting  himself  with  ardour  to  the  Eleatic  philo- 
sophy, of  which  Euklid  was  the  great  post-Sokratic  ex- 
ponent. He  subsequently  entered  upon  a  prolonged 
period  of  travel,  visiting  first  Ionia,  and  then  Gyrene 
and  Egypt,  and  occupying  himself  with  mathematical  and 
other  studies.  Of  more  influence  on  his  subsequent  in- 
tellectual development  was  his  journey  to  Italy,  where 
he  became  more  intimately  acquainted  with  the  Pytha- 
gorean system,  and  more  thoroughly  assimilated  its  doc- 
trines, than  previously.  Possibly  this  influence  induced 
him  to  intermeddle  with  the  political  affairs  of  Syrakuse. 
It  was  on  his  way  home  thence  to  Athens,  that  he  was 
(under  circumstances  variously  related)  captured  and 
sold  into  slavery  ;  a  state  in  which  he  might  have 
remained  but  for  the  interposition  of  his  friend,  Annikeris, 
the  Cyrenaic,  who  ransomed  him.  On  his  arrival  at  Athens, 
about  forty  years  of  age,  he  founded  his  school  in  the 
groves  of  Akademos,  subsequently  purchasing  the  garden 


Epoch  III.]  PLATO.  55 

on  the  hill  Kolonos,  as  its  perpetual  possession.  With 
the  exception  of  two  further  fruitless  expeditions  to  Sicily, 
he  remained  in  Athens,  devoting  himself  to  teaching  and 
writing  for  the  remainder  of  his  life,  which  terminated 
B.C.  347. 

Plato's  Philosophy. 

Plato  is  the  first  ancient  thinker  of  whom  we  possess 
anything  more  than  fragments.  All  Plato's  works  are 
exoteric,  that  is,  suited  not  only  for  the  school,  but  for 
cultured  readers  generally.  Critics,  ancient  and  modern, 
have  exercised  their  wits  in  determining  which  of  the 
writings  that  have  come  down  as  Plato's  are  genuine,  and 
which  are  the  works  of  disciples.  Even  in  Antiquity 
attempts  were  made  to  fix  the  order  of  the  Platonic 
Dialogues  in  a  systematic  manner.  In  connexion  with 
modern  Platonic  exegesis,  it  is  sufficient  to  cite  the  names 
of  Schleiermacher  (Plato's  Lehen  und  Schriften),  Socher 
(  Ueher  Plato's  Scliriften),  Stallbaum  (in  his  critical  edition 
of  Plato's  works),  Hermann  (Geschichte  der  Platonischen 
Philosophie,  ZeWer  (Philosophie  der  GriecJien),  Grote  (Plato 
and  the  other  companions  of  SoJcrates),  and  Jowett  (Plato's 
works  translated  into  English). 

The  content  of  Plato's  philosophy  naturally  falls  into 
the  well-known  division  of  Dialectics,  Physics,  and  Ethics, 
although  it  is  doubtful  if  he  himself  so  formulated  it.  The 
positive  doctrines  have  to  be  sought  out  in  the  various 
dialogues,  each  of  which  is,  generally  speaking,  devoted 
to  the  elucidation  of  some  one  point,  but  all  of  which 
possess  a  merely  negative  and  preparatory  in  addition  to 
their  positive  side.  Plato,  like  any  modern  philosophic 
writer,  always  pre-supposes  in  his  readers  a  knowledge  of 
the  chief  philosophical  literature  of  his  time.  His  polemic, 
in  common  with  that  of  his  master  Sokrates,  is  mainly 
directed  against  prevalent  conceptions,  and  the  doctrines 
of  the  Sophists  ;  though  there  were  not  wanting  sly  shafts 
aimed  at  the  Sokratic  teaching  itself. 

In  the  Theaisetus  and  the  Parmenides,  "common 
sense "  is  attacked ;  its  object  is  shown  to  possess  no 
stability,  and  its  existence  to  be  at  the  best,  probability 
or  opinion  merely.     The  goal  of  all  these  discussions  is  to 


56  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

produce  scepticism  of  ordinary  notions  and  the  dictates 
of  unreflective  perception  ;  and  is  thus  identical  with  the 
conviction  of  ignorance,  which  it  was  the  aim  oC  the 
Sokratic  Dialectic  to  bring  about.  But  this  is  with  Plato 
only  the  recoil  previous  to  the  philosophic  spring  about  to 
be  made.  All  philosophy  begins  with  the  recluctio  ad 
absurdum  of  common  notions.  There  is  no  true  knowledge  ; 
wisdom,  or  even  morality,  but  thaj:  at j^ Tu^.d~thTT)u gTTph i  1  o- 
_§^Mc^rej[ec"n'on.^~"The^  virtue  Qjf^^ecommon  man  is  the 
e^ct  of  chance  and — custom.  TEe  success  even  of  a 
Perikles,  is  merely  due  to  a  happy  concurrence  of  character 
and  circumstances.  In  the  ordinary  sense  the  man  is 
termed  brave,  even  though  he  fights  from  fear ;  .but_  no 
_actioiiJfijceally^yirtjwu^w^  full 

conscioiisness_  gf^lts^grounds.  It  is  not,  as  with  the 
Sophists,  the  individual  perception  or  opinion  that  sums 
up  the  truth  for  man,  but  that  which  is  divine  and  univer- 
sal in  him,  namely,  the  reflective,  self-comprehending 
Reason.  Plato  draws  the  distinction  between  impulse  and 
rational  will,  and  shows  that  where  pleasure  is  made  of 
set  purpose  the  sole  principle  of  action,  the  reverse  of 
pleasure  is  attained.     (Gorgias.) 

The  subjective  condition  of  true__knowlfid^e  is  jDhilo- 
sophical  yearning  or  desire.  Neither  the  all-knuwing 
(crocfios:)  nor  the  wholly  ignorant  (d/xa^-^s)  is  concerned 
therewith,  but  only  the  lover  of  wisdom  (^tA.o(To</)os), 
he,  namely,  who  represents  the  mean  between  perfect  know- 
ledge and  absolute  ignorance.  The  philosophical  impulse 
is  the  germ  from  which  art,  morality  and  science  proceed, 
but  it  needs  training  and  nourishment.  The  learning 
which  is  the  nourishment  of  the  impulse,  is  the  study  of 
the  beautiful.  Hence  music*  is  named  as  the  introduction 
to  philosophy.  Mathematics  is  another  stage  midway 
between  sense-perception  and  intellectual  intuition.  But 
the  highest  of  all  is  the  dialectical  art.  (Phsedo,  Bejyuhlic.) 
Dialectics  stands  in  opposition  to  the  Rhetoric  of  the 
Sophists,  which  only  teaches  the  art  of  expression.  It  is 
injialogue,  that  by  the^ifting  and^  opposition  of  cojftmpn 

*  "  Music,"  it  must  be   borne  in  mind,  with   the  ancients  meant 
general  culture,  excluding  mathematics  and  philosophy. 


Epoch  III.]  PLATO.  57 

opinions,  the  true,  the  -univerBal  is  evolved.  Antithetic 
procedure  is  best  for  clear  conceiving,  as  the  consequences 
of  a  conception  and  its  opposite  are  then  drawn  from  its 
definition.  But  while  the  ironic  method  of  Sokrates,  the 
Sophists,  and  of  Zeno,  is  commended  as  a  means,  yet  viewed 
as  an  end  in  itself  it  is  no  less  condemned.  The  ascent  to 
a  correctly  defined  conception  does  not  exhaust  the  process. 
When  it  is  reached,  its  grounds  and  its  relations  to  other 
concepts  have  further  to  be  determined.  Plato,  in  his 
most  subtle  analyses,  never  loses  sight  of  the  fact  that 
philosophy  is  and  must  be  a  unity  or  nothing.  Thus  the 
desire  or  love  of  knowledge  (^eros)  is  not  sufScient  to  make 
the  philosopher.  He  must  understand  and  practise  the 
dialectical  art.  In  the  Symposium  Sokrates  is  treated 
as  the  incarnation  of  the  Eros  or  love  of  wisdom.  Plato, 
it  should  be  observed,  speaks  somewhat  differently  in 
different  places  of  Dialectics.  Sometimes  he  identifies 
it  with  truth  or  philosophy  itself,  while  at  others,  he  more 
consistently  sj^eaks  of  it  as  the  ante-chamber  to  knowledge, 
philosophy  or  truth. 

Most  of  the  more  specifically  dialectical  among  Plato's 
dialogues  {e.g.,  the  These tetus,  the  Sophists,  the  Par- 
menides,  the  Kratylos)  are  occupied  with  the  attempt  to 
discover  a  via  media  between  Eleaticism  and  Herakleitism, 
between  the  conception  of  Being  as  one,  self-existent,  im- 
movable, unchangeable,  and  the  manifold,  independent, 
moving,  changeful  world  of  sense-perception.  Plato  saw  a 
half-truth  in  both  of  these  doctrines ;  he  also  saw  their  seem- 
ingly contradictory  nature.  Hence  his  aim  was  to  resolve 
this  contradiction  in  a  higher  unity.  This  could  only  be 
efi^ected  on  Platonic  principles  by  their  mutual  trituration, 
so  to  speak.  In  the  Parmenides,*  Plato  seeks  to  show  that 
Eleaticism  is  destroyed  by  its  own  arguments,  since  its 
negation  of  the  manifold,  &c.,  leads  to  fully  as  great  contra- 
dictions as  the  opposite  doctrine.  The  One  in  and  above 
the  Many,  Being  in  Becoming,  Identity  in  Difference,  and  that 
which,  existent,  cannot  be  thought  of,  except  as  limited 
by  non-existence  is  variously  designated  by  Plato  as  ovrois 
ov,  as  A.oyos  (a  word  first  employed  in  a  philosophical  sense 

*  The  genuineness  of  the  Parmenides  has  been  more  than  once 
disputed,  but  to  all  appearance  on  ground  scarcely  adequate. 


58  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  TIL 

by  Herakleitos,  whose  subsequent  history  is  both  curious  and 
important  as  regards  speculative  thought),  as  oucrta,  as 
yeVos,  as  ctSo?  vo-qrov,  or  finally  as  ISea.  The  last  term 
is  the  one  with  which  Plato's  system  is  most  character- 
istically associated.  What  Plato  understood  by  Ideas  is  at 
once  seen  when  we  remember  that  he  says  there  are  as 
many  Ideas  as  general  names.  The  synthesis  of  qualities 
cojmoted  in  a  universal  term  constitute  the  archetypal 
form  or  Idea  of  the  concrete  individuals  which  are  (denoted 
by  it.  Thus  the  general  names  "  house,"  "  bed,"  "  animal," 
stand  for  the  self-existent  archetypal  ideas  of  all  the  par- 
ticulars and  singulars  falling  severally  under  them,  that  is 
at  once  for  all  particular  kinds  of  houses,  beds  or  animals, 
and  for  every  individual  house,  bed  or  animal.  Plato's  via 
media  between  the  Eleatic  changeless  one  and  the  Herak- 

leitan   flux   of  the  m^^ny  nnnsisfprl  in    |.Via   systp^TTi   nfUflpaSj 

A^hich  showed  a  hierarchical  order  of  gradation  from  the 
highest  and  most  alistract  <;(»ncept  to  the  concrete..real  of 
experience.  Thus  with  i'lato  the  inchoate  "  non-existent  " 
world  oTpure  sense  was  no  less  an  element  in  the  reality 
of  consciousness  than  the  self-existent  world  of  pure  in- 
telligibility. The  properly  non-existent  world  of  sense 
acquired  a  pseudo-existence  through  its  participation  in 
the  world  of  ideas,  the  synthesis  being  our  real  world.  But 
the  essence  of  the  Platonic  ideas  is  not  exhausted  in  their 
being  the  self-existent  basis  of  the  class  they  cover  ;  they 
must  also  be  regarded  as  potences  positing  their  own  ends. 
AVith  this  notion  of  end  we  get  into  the  region  of  ethics 
and  ontology  or  teleology.  In  the  PJisedo,  we  are  expressly 
warned  against  conceiving  the  causal  conditions  of  things 
as  their  true  basis  (atria),  for  this  latter  can  only  lie  in 
their  end  or  purpose.  The  teleological  aspect  of  individual 
things  or  of  classes  of  things  is  indicated  by  the  comparatives 
better,  best,  which  presuppose  their  relation  to  an  absolute 
universal  ideal  good,  as  the  ultimate  end,  that  in  which  all 
other  ends,  and,  a  fortiori,  all  ideas,  are,  so  to  speak,  gathered 
up  and  concentrated.  When  we  consider  the  ontological 
system  of  ideas  as  also  a  teleological  system  of  ends,  it  is 
evident  that  this  system  must  culminate  in  an  Idea  which 
presents  itself  as  the  highest  end,  that  to  which  all  other 
Ideas  as  ends  tend  to  approach  in  varying  degrees. 


Epoch  III.]  PLATO.  59 

Thus  with  Plato  the  highest  Idea  or  ultimate  end-in- 
itself  was  manifested  in  a  multitude  of  subordinate  ideas  or 
"ends  ;"  and  thus  the  problem  of  Pythagorean  and  Eleatic, 
the  problem  of  the  One  and  the  Many  was  solved,  the  vo9s 
of  Anaxagoras,  and  the  "  good  "  of  Sokrates  being  embraced 
in  the  solution.  Hence,  too,  Plato  achieved  what  his  friend 
Euklid  the  Megaric  had  attempted,  namely,  an  ethical 
Monism  on  the  Sokratic  lines.  By  Plato's  highest  and 
comprehensive  principle  of  the  Good  is  to  be  understood 
the  universal  world-order,  natural  no  less  than  moral. 
The  absolute  end  or  purpose  as  the  "  ov  oi/ro^? "  is  the 
object  of  Dialectics,  inasmuch  as  this  science  leads  from 
the  lower  ideas,  which  are  the  determinations  of  things,  to 
that  which  is  the  determination  of  all  determinations  them- 
selves. But  the  dialectician  must  not  be  satisfied  merely 
with  ascending  from  the  lowest  to  the  highest,  he  must 
also  be  able  to  deduce  all  lower  ideas  and  all  particular  things 
from  this  highest  principle.  In  his  later  life  Plato  seems 
to  have  more  and  more  tended  to  Pythagoreanism,  or  at 
least  to  a  Pythagorean  mode  of  statement.  This  appears 
most  prominently  in  the  PMlehos.  The  mathematical 
treatment  of  the  doctrine  of  ideas  which  is  there  attempted 
leads  to  results  almost  identical  with  the  Pythagorean 
theories.  The  idea  of  the  good  is  identified  with  the  Deity 
or  divine  Eeason  as  well  as  with  the  Pythagorean  Noetic 
One.  The  high  estimation  of  the  mathematical  sciences, 
which  is  noticeable  in  the  later  writings,  is  not  discoverable 
in  the  Bepublic  and  other  of  the  more  important  dialogues, 
where  they  are  spoken  of  merely  as  one  of  the  preparatory 
stages  from  mere  "  opinion  "  to  the  higher  philosophical 
insights  obtained  through  the  dialectical  faculty,  superior 
indeed  to  the  first  but  inferior  to  the  second,  inasmuch 
as  their  subject-matter  is  still  within  the  region  of  sense. 

Plato's  doctrine  of  reminiscence,  as  presented  in  the  Meno, 
the  Phsedrus  and  elsewhere,  is  founded  on  the  notion  of 
the  ultimate  identity  of  the  divine  and  human  minds.  The 
soul  in  its  union  with  a  material  body  enters  on  a  period  of 
degradation  in  which  it  has  fallen  from  its  high  estate  as 
a  pure  existent  intelligible  or  formal  essence,  and  become 
contaminated  with  the  non-existent  world  of  sense.  But, 
however  low  it  has  sunk,  it  never  entirely  loses  traces  of 


60  GKEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

its  origin.  The  possibility  of  its  regaining  its  lost  birth- 
right, nay,  even  the  possibility  of  philosophy  itself  lies  in 
this  fact,  in  that  it  has  a  remembrance  of  the  higher 
realities  it  was  wont  to  contemplate,  and  which  it  is  the 
object  of  the  philosopher  to  disentangle  from  the  confusion 
of  sense,  and  rehabilitate  as  far  as  may  be  in  their  purity. 
-      This,  which  is  the  end  of  the  philosopher's  life,  can  only  be 

^  proximately  attained  in  this  sphere  of  existence  ;  yet  the 
soul  illumined  by  the  philosophic  contemplation  may  rise 
in  proportion  to  its  light  the  more"  speedily  to  be  re- 
absorbed into  that  divine  essence,  in  which  the  material, 

/  the  sensible,  has  vanished,  and  the  formal,  and  the  intel- 
ligible, alone  remains.  How  much  of  this  as  of  other 
portions  of  Plato's  doctrine  was  merely  poetry  or  allegory, 
it  is  impossible  to  decide  with  certainty,  but  there  is 
no  serious  reason  for  doubting  that  it  was  really  held  by 
Plato. 

Plato's  physical  speculations  are  contained  almost  in 
their  entirety  in  the  Timseus.  Inasmuch  as  the  material 
universe  is  only  the  object  of  perception  and  not  of  pure 
intellection,  no  such  strict  deduction  of  principles  can  be 
expected  in  dealing  with  it,  as  in  subjects  capable  of  the' 
application  of  pure  Dialectic.  The  most  that  can  be 
furnished  is  a  body  of  probable  opinion.  The  question 
immediately  arises,  what  is  that  which  must  be  added  to 
the  system  or  complex  of  Ideas  in  order  that  it  may 
appear  as  Nature,  or  in  other  words,  as  the  Good  in  the 
harmonious  order  of  the  sensible  universe.  The  answer  is, 
that,  in  the  first  place,  the  superadded  principle  must  be 
foreign  to  the  system  of  ideas  itself ;  the  one  being  per  se 
the  totality  of  absolute  Being,  the  other  must  be  that  of 
absolute  non-Being ;  since  the  one  is  the  principle  of  all- 
embracing  and  eternal  unity,  the  other  must  be  that  of 
self-contradictory,  evanescent  multiplicity.*  This  principle 
must  in  short  be  none  other  than  that  unqualified,  form- 
less, inconceivable  matter  which  is  the  object  of  pure  sense. 
Pure  sense  must  not  be  confounded  with  conscious  percep- 
tion which  involves  a  participation  in  the  ideal  or  logical ; 

*  It  may  be  observed  in  passing,  that  this  is  simply  a  roundabout 
mode  of  stating  the  Aristotelian  distinction  of  form  and  matter,  which 
all  the  dialogues  of  Plato  are  struggling  to  express. 


Epoch  III.]  PLATO.  61 

it  is  rather  mere  inchoate  siih-conscions  feeling  (the  hlinde 
Anschauung  of  Kant).  This  is  the  properly  non-existent 
element  in  the  real  world,  and  this  it  is  which  added  to, 
or  latlier  limiting,  and,  so  to  si)eak,  blurring  the  ideal 
world  transforms  it  into  Nature  or  the  world  of  actual 
experience.  The  purely  sensible  or  non-existent  as 
opposed  to  the  purely  intelligble  or  existent  object  seems 
to  be  identified  by  Plato  as  by  Aristotle,  with  pure 
extension  or  space.  Plato  may  have  well  seen  in  space 
the  medium  by  which  the  self-contained  ideas  were 
confounded  with  one  another  and  with  their  negation, 
in  the  foi  m  of  concrete  objects. 

The  foregoing  doctrine,  though  not  expressed  in  so 
many  words  by  Plato,  is  implied  more  or  less  throughout 
his  writings,  and  is  the  only  consistent  mode  of  stating 
in  a  few  words  his  position.  It  is  introduced  here  as 
assisting  the  student  to  understand  the  transition  from 
the  dialectical  to  the  physical  side  of  his  philosojDhy,  In 
the  Timseus  the  universe  is  conceived  as  an  animated  being, 
"  a  blessed  God,"  created  by  a  Demiiirge  or  divine  artificer, 
a  conception,  however,  difScult  to  reconcile  with  the 
other  side  of  the  sj^stem,  and  illustrating  the  looseness 
and  essentially  unsystematic  character  of  Plato's  ex- 
position where  it  is  so  often  hard  to  distinguish  between 
philosophy  and  poetry.  But  it  seems  that  Plato  identified 
his  creator  with  the  sujDreme  "  Idea "  or  the  "  Good." 
The  soul  of  the  world  which  pervades  its  every  part, 
manifesting  itself  in  the  numbers  and  harmony  of  the 
spheres  no  less  than  in  the  laws  regulating  mundane 
phenomena — was  created  prior  to  the  body  or  material  of 
the  universe.  Time  is  coincident  with  its  formation. 
The  universe  represents  the  best  possible  of  worlds. 
As  the  chaotic  matter  took  form  and  shape  it  assumed 
determinate  mathematical  figures  and  relations.  Thus 
the  elementary  constituents  of  fire  are  of  pyramidal 
figure,  those  of  water,  icosahedral,  those  of  air  octahedral, 
and  those  of  earth  cubical.  The  spheres  once  constituted 
the  deity  proceeds  to  the  creation  of  living  beings.  First 
in  order  come  the  heavenly  gods  (which  are  identified  in 
part  at  best  with  the  stars  and  other  celestial  bodies) ; 
secondly,  the  creatures  inhabiting  the  air ;  thirdly,  those 


62  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

living  in  water ;  and  finally,  those  whose  dwelling-place 
is  the  earth.  Plato  then  gives  a  mythical  description  of 
the  origin  of  those  inferior  species  of  animals  which  the 
supreme  deity  himself  has  not  formed,  but  whose  creation 
is  delegated  to  the  lower  gods,  with  the  exception  of 
whatsoever  is  immortal  in  their  constitution.  Man  is  the 
analogue  of  the  universe,  in  so  far  as,  like  the  world,  he 
consists  of  body  and  soul  in  mysterious  unity.  His  soul 
is  of  a  dual  or  indeed  triple  nature.  In  the  head  is  lodged 
the  divine  and  immortal  part ;  in  the  breast  the  mortal  and 
human  part,  consisting  of  the  passions ;  while  the  liver 
and  spleen  were  constructed  and  placed  where  they  are 
for  the  purpose  of  divination  and  prediction  of  the  future. 
The  later  chapters  of  the  Timseus  show  that  Plato,  like 
most  of  his  contemporaries,  was  a  believer  in  metem- 
psychosis, and  contain  some  curious  and  fanciful  applica- 
tions of  that  widespread  and  time-honoured  doctrine. 
Such  is  a  brief  outline  of  Plato's  cosmical  theory. 

The  essence  of  the  Platonic  metaphysic  we  have  seen  to 
consist  in  the  doctrine,  that  to  every  concept  or  general 
name,  there  corresponds  an  eternal,  self-existent  essence  or 
idea ;  that  the  system  of  ideas  thence  arising  has  at  once 
as  its  basis  and  completion,  the  idea  of  the  Good  which  is 
the  common  principle  alike  of  being  and  knowing,  and 
from  which  therefore  all  subordinate  concepts  and  ideas 
are  deducible  (according  to  the  Philehos  on  mathematical 
principles).  This  "  good,"  it  will  have  been  apparent,  is 
aesthetic  and  teleological  as  well  as  specially  ethical. 
But  inasmuch  as  it  is  the  object  of  all  philosophy,  it  is  of 
course  none  the  less  so  of  Ethics.  In  this  connection  we 
have  to  regard  it  as  constituting  the  content  of  the  human 
will.  Plato  in  the  Thesetetiis  expresses  himself  ve- 
hemently against  the  Cyi'enaic  Hedonists  who  would 
make  pleasure  the  chief  good.  In  the  Philehos  (as  in  the 
Bepuhlic  and  elsewhere,  though  at  less  length)  he  de- 
velops the  thesis  that  only  in  the  Beautiful  and,  a  fortiori^ 
in  the  Proportionate  (since  to  Plato  beauty  consisted  in 
nothing  but  symmetry,  proportion,  and  harmony)  does 
the  good  lie,  and  hence  that  all  excess  either  on  the  side 
of  asceticism  or  indulgence  is  evil,  a  position  in  consonance 
with  his  general  attitude.     Intemperate  and  exaggerated 


Epoch  III.]  PLATO.  63 

tendencies  and  conduct  he  regards  as  diseases  of  the  soul, 
since  they  imply  the  ascendency  of  the  merely  human  and 
animal  over  the  divine  portions,  in  other  words  a  lack  of 
the  regulating  power  of  insight  and  reason,  and  a  conse- 
quent blind  irrational  play  of  impulses,  indicating  a  dis- 
turbance of  normal  functions,  corresponding  to  that 
observable  in  bodily  disease.  We  have  seen  how  Plato 
identifies  the  ethical  with  the  sesthetic  chief  good  which 
was  at  the  same  time  the  highest  end.  We  shall,  therefore, 
not  be  surprised  at  his  teleological  definition  of  Virtue  as 
the  adaptability  of  the  life  to  its  end — a  definition  which 
embraces  all  particular  virtues  and  is  coincident  with 
Justice.  Virtue  is  to  be  pursued  as  an  end  in  itself,  and 
on  no  account  for  subsidiary  ends,  such  as  pleasure  and 
pain,  reward  and  punishment.  To  do  evil  is  always 
worse  than  to  suifer  evil. 

In  the  Republic  we  have  a  presentation  of  the  "  good  " 
in  the  form  of  perfect  virtue  or  justice  as  embodied  in  the 
social  order  of  a  commonwealth,  in  the  same  way  that  in 
the  Timseus  we  had  a  presentation  of  the  manner  in  which 
this  same  idea  embodied  itself  as  harmony  in  the  natural 
order  of  the  cosmos.  The  state  is  nothing  but  a  magnified 
individual.  The  highest  function  of  the  state  is  the 
training  of  its  citizens  to  be  virtuous.  The  orders  in  the 
state  must  correspond  to  the  virtues  of  the  human  soul, 
consisting  of  the  rulers,  whose  specific  virtue  is  wisdom, 
corresponding  to  the  divine  part ;  the  guardians  or  warriors 
whose  virtue  is  courage,  corresponding  to  the  emotional, 
active,  or  human  part ;  and  the  traders  and  labourers 
whose  virtue  is  self-control  and  obedience,  corresponding 
to  the  part  of  the  soul  concerned  with  nutrition  and  the 
organic  functions.*  There  are  to  be  no  private  interests 
or  wealth,  but  all  things  are  to  be  in  common.  Neither 
is  marriage,  or  the  family  relation  to  be  recognised.  The 
condition  of  the  realization  of  this  ideal  state  lies  in  the 
assumption  of  the  helm  of  affairs  by  statesmen  who  are  at 
the  same  time  philosophers.  This  platonic  Utopia,  though 
based  on  the  then  actually  existing  Lacedemonian  polity, 

*  The  ancients  knew  nothing  of  any  hard  and  fast  distinction 
between  the  "  soul "  and  the  life  of  the  organism ;  the  one  was  a  part 
of  the  other. 


64  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

Plato  supplemented  in  his  later  years  by  a  modified 
version  elaborated  in  the  Laws  which  was  put  forward  as 
more  easy  of  attainment. 

Plato  can  hardly  be  said  to  have  formulated  a  system 
proper.  He  retained  too  much  of  the  Sokratic  spirit  and 
method  of  pretended  ignorance  ever  to  permit  himself  the 
expression  of  a  decided  judgment.  The  form,  moreover, 
which  he  adopted  for  his  writings  rendered  this  impossi- 
ble. His  views  on  the  various  departments  of  philosophy 
are  not  grouped  in  any  way,  and  even  those  on  any  one 
subject,  often  conflicting,  have  generally  to  be  gathered 
together  from  several  different  dialogues.  Under  these 
circumstances  the  difficulty  of  furnishing  a  condensed 
account  of  true  Platonism  is  sufficiently  obvious.  Plato 
may  be  considered  as  the  founder  of  what  is  now  known  as 
"  Theory  of  Knowledge."  The  pre-Sokratic  thinkers  had 
inquired  for  the  principles  of  Being ;  Sokrates  opposed  to 
their  inquiry  that  as  to  the  principle  of  Knowing ;  Plato, 
Tvhile  starting  from  the  standpoint  of  Sokrates,  sought  to 
show  that  the  two  inquiries  were  identical,  that  Being  in- 
volved Knowing,  as  Knowing  involved  Being.  Plato  was 
thus  the  first  consistent  Idealist.  The  only  existence  to 
him  was  the  logical,  the  Ideal ;  which  was  limited  and 
confounded  by  the  non-existent  Sensible. 

Surprise  has  sometimes  bc^n  expressed  at  Plato's  includ- 
ing, besides  abstract  concepts  proper,  i.e.,  such  as  express 
qualities,  "  natural  kinds  "  or  "  class  names  "  among  his 
eternal  self-existent  ideas.  To  us  it  seems  that  it  was  in 
these  latter  that  he  believed  himself  to  have  found  the 
bridge  between  the  seose-manifold  of  experience  and  the 
intelligibles  of  Dialectics.  "  Natural  Kinds,"  in  other 
words,  universals  connoting  a  ready-made  synthesis  and 
only  awaiting  the  "  here"  and  "now  "  of  sense  for  their 
concrete  realisation,  were  plainly  the  link  between  the 
empirical  and  the  intelligible  worlds,  between  the  world 
of  change  and  multiplicity  given  in  ordinary  conscious- 
ness, and  that  world  of  abstract  ideas,  to  the  contempla- 
tion of  which  the  philosopher  aspired.  The  objects  of 
the  real  world  bore,  doubtless,  to  Plato,  much  the  same 
relation  to  the  natural  kinds  which  denoted  them,  as  the 
system  of  ideas  itself  bore  to  the  Supreme  Idea. 


Epoch  III.]  ARISTOTLE.  65 

There  are  some  stuclents  who  may  be  inclined  to 
wonder  at  Plato's  deification  of  the  concept-form  or 
universal ;  at  what  seems  to  be  mere  logical  subtlety 
being  constituted  "our  being's  aim  and  end."  Such 
persons  forget  the  fact  that  education  and  culture 
itself  is  nothing  other  than  self-universalisation.  Every 
advance  the  individual  makes  in  the  higher  life  of 
thought  means  a  breaking  down  of  the  limits  which  con- 
fine him  to  the  "  here,"  the  "  this,"  and  the  "  now  ;  "  in 
short,  in  a  sense  a  suspension,  or  at  least,  an  ignoring  of 
those  space-and-time  relations  which  rule  supreme  in 
the  every-day  world  of  his  and  his  neighbours'  "  con- 
cerns." Listen  to  the  conversation  of  a  company  of 
tradesmen,  or  women ;  of  what  does  it  consist,  but  of 
gossip  immediately  bearing  on  concrete  personalities  and 
their  surroundings;  every  thing  turns  on  this.  Listen,  on 
the  other  hand,  to  the  conversation  of  a  company  of 
thinkers,  and  it  will  in  all  probability  be  found  to  consist 
of  discussion  concerning,  not  the  interests  of  any  concrete 
person  or  persons,  leastways  qua  concrete,  but  of  things 
and  places  or  events  probably  far  distant  in  time  or  space, 
but  at  all  events  in  their  abstract  and  general  relations 
and  altogether  aj)art  from  personalities  as  such  and  their 
interests.  It  may  be  permitted  us  to  regard  this  at  least 
as  one  of  the  side-truths  shadowed  forth  in  the  work  of 
Plato.  With  this  concluding  observation,  we  pass  on  to 
Plato's  great  pupil  and  successor,  Aristotle. 


ARISTOTLE. 


The  birth  of  Aristotle  was  cast  in  one  of  the  most 
critical  periods  of  Grecian  history.  The  old  independent 
political  life  of  the  Greek  cities  was  being  extinguished 
by  the  monarch  of  a  state  that  had  hitherto  taken  little 
or  no  part  in  the  affairs  of  Greece.  It  was  at  Stageiros,  or 
Stagira— a  city  of  this  rising  state,  destined  within  the 
next  half-century  to  become  the  master  of  the  greater 
part  of  the  then  known  world— that  Aristotle  was  born 
(B.C.    385).      His    father,    Nikomachos,   and   grandfather, 


66  GKEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

Machaon,  were  both  phj^sicians,  an  interesting  circum- 
stance to  the  student  of  heredit3^  Losing  his  father  when 
a  boy,  Aristotle  was  early  thrown  on  his  own  resources, 
and  at  seventeen  years  of  age,  came  to  seek  his  fortune  in 
Athens,  where  Plato,  then  in  the  prime  of  life,  was 
attracting  to  his  lectures  the  philosophically-disposed 
among  his  fellow  citizens.  Aristotle  seems  to  have  found 
the  leisure,  in  spite  of  his  own  professional  avocations  as 
apothecar}^,  to  become  a  regular  attendant  at  the  Academy. 
Some  years  later  he  set  up  as  a  professor  of  Ehetoric, 
but  after  Plato's  death,  left  Athens,  and  repaired  with  his 
fellow-pupil,  Xenokrates,  to  Hermeias,  the  tyrant  of 
Atarneus,  whose  brother's  daughter  he  subsequently 
married.  On  the  death  of  Hermeias,  he  went  to  reside  in 
the  island  of  Mytilene,  till  called  away  by  the  offer  of 
Philip  of  Macedon,  to  entrust  him  with  the  education  of 
his  son  Alexander,  then  thirteen  years  old.  Aristotle 
remained  at  the  court  of  Macedon  four  years,  and  did  not 
quit  the  country  for  a  further  period  of  four  years,  when 
he  returned  to  Athens  and  established  himself  as  teacher 
of  philosophy  in  the  Lyceum,  a  building  deriving  its 
name  from  the  circumstance  of  its  standing  opposite  the 
temple  of  Apollo  Lykeios.  The  name  "  perijDatetic,"  which 
clung  to  Aristotle's  school,  arose  from  his  habit  of  pacing 
its  halls  while  lecturing.  His  activity  as  lecturer  only 
lasted  thirteen  years,  after  which,  in  consequence  of  a 
political  accusation,  he  left  Athens  for  Chalkis,  where  he 
died,  B.C.  322,  just  one  year  after  his  pupil,  Alexander  the 
Great. 

Aristotle's  Philosophy. 

The  features  mainly  distinguishing  the  writings  of 
Aristotle  from  those  of  Plato,  are  their  strictly  philoso23hical 
character,  there  being  no  trace  in  them  of  any  artistic 
purpose.  A  legend  relates  that  though  Aristotle  began  his 
literary  career  by  the  composition  of  dialogues  after  the 
manner  of  Plato,  he  soon  abandoned  that  form  in  despair 
of  ever  approaching  the  master.  In  addition  to  these 
dialogues,  he  wrote  other  popular  pieces,  to  which  allusions 
are  made  by  many  ancient  writers,  besides  Aristotle  him- 
self, but  these  have  all  perished  with  the  exception  of  one 


Epoch  III.]  AEISTOTLE.  67 

or  two  fragments.  Aristotle's  writings  have  reached  ns 
in  a  state  of  great  confusion,  and  in  some  cases  corruption, 
while  several  treatises  {e.g.,  the  Eudemean  and  the  "  great " 
Ethics)  handed  down  as  the  Stagirite's,  are  now  univer- 
sally recognised  as  the  compilations  of  disciples.  Several 
complete  editions  of  Aristotle  have  appeared  since  the 
Aldine,  published  at  Florence,  in  five  folio  volumes,  in  the 
15th  century.  The  best  is  generally  considered  to  be  that 
of  Bekker  and  Brandis,  issued  under  the  auspices  of  the 
Berlin  Academy  of  Sciences  (4  vols.,  1831-35). 

In  the  Aristotelian  philosophy,  the  departments  of 
Logic,  Physics,  and  Ethics  become  even  more  definitely 
pronounced  than  in  the  Platonic.  Eecognising,  wdth 
Plato,  the  indwelling  yearning  for  knowledge  as  the 
basis  of  philosopliy.  Aristotle  maintains  that  philosophy 
is^othing  but  the  extension  and  methodisation  of  common 
experience  ;  that  it  does  not,  as  Plato  contended,  involve  a 
complete  break  with  the  sense-manifold,  but  that  on  the_ 
contrary  it  has  its  origin  in  common  perception,  or  in 
other  words,  in  particular  objects.  ^ExjDerience  is  merely 
constituted  out  of  the  successive  recognition  of  likeness 
in  jDercepJions.  Common  sense  thus  involves  a  universal 
element  no  less  than  philosophy  itself,  although  its  relation 
tophiTosopby  is  that  of  a  particular.  The  whole  of  know- 
lec^  is  a  scale  or  ladder  in  which  there  is,  no  break^jTui, 
a  continuous  progressive  ascent  from  the  singular  sense- 
perception  to  the~higliest  generalisation  of  speculative 
thmight. 

The  occupation  with  mere  logical  forms,  the  uni- 
versals  of  Plato,  abstracts  from  an  essential  element  in 
all  existence,  the  higher  no  less  than  the  lower — namely, 
the  material  element.  The  grounds  of  the  reason  can 
never,  according  to  Aristotle,  attain  to  the  accuracy  of 
sense-perception.  Nevertheless,  Aristotle  assumes  the 
fundamental  position  of  speculative  thought.  Ontology, 
or  the  "first  philosophy"  of  Aristotle,  inasmuch  as  it 
professes  to  deduce  the  existent  from  principles,  presup- 
poses the  question,  w^hat  is  a  principle  ?  The  answer  to 
this  question  is  to  be  found  in  the  four  different  senses 
of  the  words  ahia  and  ap^-q.  The  first  book  of  the  Meta- 
physics, which   is   the  earliest   attempt  at  a  systematic 

F  2 


68  GEEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

history  of  philosophy,  is  an  endeavour  to  illustrate  these 
four  different  senses  by  the  various  systems  of  philosophy. 
With  the  lonians  the  principle  or  cause  was  matter  ;  with 
the  Pythagoreans, /onw  ;  with  Empedokles,  efficient  cause; 
with  Anaxagoras,  end  or  final  cause.  By  matter  (yX-q) 
Aristotle  understands  the  warp  or  basis,  so  to  speak,  to  be 
operated  on,  or  which  becomes.  Thus  bronze  is  the  matter 
of  the  statue,  the  acorn  of  the  oak,  the  premisses  of  the 
conclusion,  the  instrument  of  the  music  it  produces,  the 
component  sounds  of  the  octave,  the  letters  of  which  it 
consists  of  the  word,  etc.,  etc.  Matter  is  in  short  the  un- 
determined real.  In  the  instances  given  it  is  of  course 
only  relatively  undetermined,  but,  em^Dloyed  in  an  onto- 
logical  sense,  the  term  means  the  ahsolutehj  undetermined, 
corresponding  to  the  unqnalified  Infinite  of  Anaximandros, 
or  the  non-existent  sense-object  of  Plato.  Matter  con- 
sidered per  se,  that  is,  abstracted  from  all  determination, 
coincides  with  the  potential.  It  is  the  mere  possibility  of 
the  Eeal ;  the  incomplete,  the  unbecome  factor  therein. 

The  second  and  opposite  principle,  that  of  form  (ixopcf}-^, 
Xdyos),  denotes  pure  determination,  the  Platonic  Idea. 
This  second  principle  is  related  to  the  first,  as  activity  to 
passivity,  as  actuality  to  potentiality.  It  is  the  figure 
into  which  the  bronze  is  fashioned,  to  constitute  it  a 
statue  ;  the  melody  which  is  produced  by  the  notes  of  the 
flute  ;  the  relation  of  the  sounds  which  give  the  octave  ;  the 
particular  conjunction  of  letters  which  make  the  word  ;  the 
articulate  whole  into  which  the  parts  are  gathered  up, 
or  the  mass  is  moulded,  etc.  In  an  ontological  sense  it  is 
of  course  pure,  absolute  determination  as  distinguished 
from  the  merely  relative  determination  of  the  instances 
given.  In  short,  the  form  of  Aristotle  corresponds  as 
nearly  as  possible  to  the  self-existent  intelligible  world  of 
Plato,  just  as  the  matter  of  Aristotle  corresponds  to  the 
non-existent  sense-world  of  Plato.  But  with  Aristotle 
there  was  no  such  thing  as  pure  form  (ideas)  existing  per 
se  and  apart  from  matter.  Form  only'existed  in  and  for 
matter,  as  a  specific  modification  of  matter.  Aristotle  is 
vehement  in  his  polemic  against  the  Platonic  Ideas,  the 
universalia  ante  res.  But,  while  to  assume  as  Plato  did,  the 
existence  of  pure  forms  apart  from  the  matter  of  which 


ErocH  III.]  ARISTOTLE.  69 

they  are  the  form,  is  inadmissible ;  it  is  equally  plain 
that  pure  unqualified  matter  can  never  be  an  object  of 
experience.  Hence,  to  Aristotle,  the  two  elements  in 
question  were  equally  essential  to»  experience,  and  to  all 
reality  whatever,  as  much  to  "  true "  as  to  emiDirical 
being.  This  Aristotelian  distinction  of  itself  marks  an 
epoch,  most  momentous  in  the  history  of  thought,  and  at 
once  clears  the  ground  of  a  mass  of  extraneous. material. 

As  regards  the  third  sense  of  the  word  princijyle  (to 
indicate  which  Aristotle  makes  use  of  a  variety  of  ex- 
pressions, but  all  of  which  are  summed  up  with  tolerable 
accuracy  in  the  well-known  scholastic  phrase  causa 
efficiens)  it  is  enough  to  remark  that  it  refers  to  the 
immediate  empirical  cause,  or  antecedent  condition, 
(efficient  cause)  of  anything,  and  is  antithetical  to  re'Ao?,  or 
the  fourth  sense  of  the  word,  which  is  that  oi  final  cause  or 
purpose.  The  reAos,  it  is  imjDortant  to  remember,  is  the 
ultimate  and  highest  form  of  the  reality  of  a  thing,  to 
the  attainment  of  which  all  the  other  forms  are  sub- 
servient, and  with  reference  to  which  they  may  be  regarded 
as  means  merely. 

The  four  factors  above  enumerated  furnish  the  data  of 
ontology.  Foremost  comes  the  negative  result  before 
mentioned,  that  neither  mere  matter,  nor  mere  form  con- 
stitute the  existent  Eeal,  but  the  union  or  synthesis  of 
matter  and  form.  This  is  insisted  upon  as  regards  matter 
against  the  Hylozoists,  as  regards  form  against  the  Eleatics 
and  Plato.  Matter  is  the  hecoming — neither  being  nor 
non-being,  but,  as  Ferrier  would  have  put  it,  more  than 
0  and  less  than  I.  There  is  no  passage  from  non-Being  to 
Being,  but  only  from  the  not-yet-existent  to  the  at-present 
existent.  The  ovo-ia  (essence),  though  sometimes  employed 
as  coincident  with  form,  is  generally  used  for  the 
synthesis  itself.  The  whole  essence  or  synthesis,  the  real 
existent,  is  also  said  to  be  constituted  out  of  the  two 
momenta,  the  genus  and  the  differentia — the  first  cor- 
responding to  matter,  and  the  second  to  form.  Thus 
Sokrates  may  be  described  as  made  ujd  of  the  matter  (genus) 
of  man  and  the  form  (differentia)  of  Sokratitij.  But  the 
synthesis  is  not  to  be  regarded  as  a  fixed  or  static  entity. 
For  Aristotle,  all  reality  is  expressed  in  the  logical  passage 


70  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

from  matter  to  form ;  that  is,  from  a  lower,  to  a  higlier, 
from  the  less  complex  to  the  more  complex — the  lower 
stage  being  related  as  matter  to  the  incoming  element,  the 
form,  which  denotes  the  higher  stage.  'Yo  take  the  above 
instance,  Sokrates  pins  the  differentia  of  Sokratity,  that 
is,  Sokrates  qua  Sokrates,  involves  a  formal  element,  over 
and  above  his  material  basis,  Athenian.  The  Athenian 
again  qua  Athenian  is  a  formal  modification  of  Ms  material 
basis,  Greek,  which  as  Athenian  he  presupposes.  Once 
more,  the  Greek  qua  Greek  is  a  formal  modification  of 
the  material  basis,  Man ;  as  Greek  he  involves  an  element 
of  form  additional  to  the  human  material  (the  common 
humanity)  of  which  he  consists,  &c.,  &c.  The  final  terminus 
a  quo  of  the  scale  is  thus  pure  undifferentiated  matter. 

We  now  turn  to  the  third  and  fourth  data  in  the  Aris- 
totelian ontology,  the  efficient  and  the  final  cause.  Here 
the  element  of  determinate  agency  comes  into  play.  The 
first  of  these,  the  conditio  sine  qua  non  of  the  existence  of  a 
thing,  may  be  regarded  as  its  material  cause ;  the  second, 
the  end  or  purpose  of  its  existence,  its  formal  cause.  In  the 
force  or  self-activity  or  actualisation  (evreA.e;(€ia)  which  is 
part  of  the  essence  of  reality,  the  two  elements  of  mover 
and  moved,  the  passive  and  the  active  are  to  be  distin- 
guished. The  first  is  the  formal,  the  second  the  material. 
The  one  is  the  agent,  the  other  the  patient.  But  this 
formative  activity,  or  subordinate  motive,  itself  presupposes 
an  end  or  purpose  which  it  is  to  accomplish,  and  this  leads 
us  to  the  final  cause  or  the  ultimate  principle  of  motion, 
that  which  moves  but  is  not  moved  — pure  energy.  But 
Aristotle  does  not  deny  substantiality  to  this  pure  energy. 
On  the  contrary,  just  as  matter  j;er  se  is  potentiality, 
alwaj's  becoming  but  never  become,  so  this  ultimate  formal 
princij)le  is  its  counterpart,  actuality,  eternal  self-sub- 
existence.  Thus  Aristotle  finds  in  this  teleological  con- 
ception of  intelligent  purpose  the  terminus  ad  quern  of 
the  scale  of  being,  which  the  notion  of  mere  form,  per  se, 
could  not  give  him.  It  is  needless  to  remind  the  reader 
that  this  aKLvrjTov  of  Aristotle  is  the  representative,  in  his 
system  of  the  sujDreme  idea  of  Plato.  It  is  not  difficult  to 
see  how  the  Neo-Platonic  harmonists  of  a  later  time  might, 
with  some  show  of  reason,  maintain  the  essential  identitj? 


Epoch  III.J  ARISTOTLE.  71 

of  the  systems  of  Aristotle  and  Plato  when  they  found  so 
many  cardinal  features  in  common. 

Aristotle  is  the  first  to  distinctly  apply  the  so-called 
cosmological  argument.  As  every  individual  object  pre- 
supposes a  moving  cause  for  all  its  changes,  so  the  universe 
itself  presupposes  an  absolute  first  mover,  a  primal  deter- 
miner of  its  as  yet  undetermined  matter.  But  Aristotle 
soon  leaves  this  mechanical  theistic  conception.  This 
principle  (TrpoiTov  kivovv)  must  be  essentially  pure  energy 
and  form,  untrammelled  b}^  matter,  pure  actuality,  in 
which  the  shadow  of  potentiality  is  not;  a  conception 
which,  it  need  scarcely  be  said,  is  hard  to  reconcile  with 
Aristotle's  assertions  of  the  inseparability  of  matter  and 
form,  or  with  his  bitter  polemic  against  the  Platonic 
system  of  ideal  ends,  which  is  its  prototype.  The 
ultimate  self-thinking  and  active  principle,  or  God  of 
Aristotle,  is  not  to  be  conceived  as  the  creator  of  the  world 
in  time  (like  the  demiurge  of  Plato),  but  rather  as  the 
immanent  actuality  of  the  world,  the  eternally  complete 
ideal  purpose  to  which  the  real  is  ever  approximating,  and 
which  is  at  the  same  time  its  ultimate  motive  principle.* 

Nature,  according  to  Aristotle,  is  the  totality  of  material 
and  moving  objects.  Change,  or  motion,  may  be  divided 
into  origination  (change  or  motion  from  the  relatively  non- 
existent to  the  relatively  existent)  and  destruction  (change 
or  motion  from  the  relatively  existent  to  the  relatively 
non-existent),  which  is  again  divided  into  the  species 
quantitative,  qualitative  and  spacial  motion ;  or  increase 
and  decrease,  change  of  quality  and  change  of  place. 
The  conditions  of  motion  are  place  or  space  and  time. 
Place  (T67ro<i)  is  the  bounding  of  the  encompassing  body. 
Time  is  the  measure  or  numerical  aspect  of  motion  or 
change.  Time  is  endless,  but  space  bounded.  The  world 
is  eternal.  The  spheres  in  wbich  the  fixed  stars  inhere, 
possess  the  most  perfect  of  all  motions — the  circular. 
The  motions  of  the  planets  are  explained  by  the  hypothesis 
of  immaterial  essences  or  subordinate  deities  inhering  in 
them.  The  spherical  earth  is  fixed  in  the  centre  of  the 
universe.  The  five  elementary  natural  substances,  ether, 
fire,  water,  air  and  earth  have  respectively  their  determi- 

*  I  mny  point  out  here  how  nearly  identical  is  Aristotle's  conceptioD 
with  the  Idea  of  Hei^el. 


72  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

nate  places  in  the  cosmic  whole.  The  place  of  the  ether 
is  the  celestial  regions.  Out  of  ether  are  formed  the 
spheres  and  celestial  bodies.  The  other  (traditional)  four 
elements  belong  to  the  terrestrial  regions,  but  are  distin- 
guished by  their  heaviness  and  lightness,  heat  and  cold, 
dryness  and  moisture,  and  are  all  found  in  various  propor- 
tions in  all  bodies.  The  matter  of  earth  is  continually 
passing  into  higher  and  higher  forms  in  the  shape  of  a 
progressive  scale  (as  it  were)  of  living  beings.  Every 
stage  in  this  formal  determination  of  course  embraces  the 
whole  of  those  below  it,  in  addition  to  its  own  special  and 
distinctive  character.  The  force  or  formative  energy  of 
living  beings  in  the  widest  sense,  is,  with  Aristotle, 
identical  with  their  souls,  or  iffvx-q-  Thus  the  capacity  or 
soul  of  the  plant  is  limited  to  nutrition  and  growth  accord- 
ing to  a  certain  figure  ;  the  animal  possesses  in  addition  to 
this  the  capacities  of  feeling,  desire,  and  locomotion ;  the 
man  again  unites  with  all  these  capacities  that  of  reason 
(voGs),  the  manifestation  of  which  is  j^artly  theoretical 
(scientific)  and  partly  practical  (moral).  The  Keason  is  sepa- 
rable into  two  elements  or  sides,  the  receptive,  determined 
and  temporal,  and  the  creative,  determining  and  eternal. 
The  first  of  these  elements  is  the  material,  the  second  the 
formal  side  of  the  Reason.  The  synthesis  of  these  two  ele- 
ments, the  natural  and  the  divine,  constitutes  the  human  soul 
or  life  of  the  man  as  man.  The  discussion  of  these  subjects 
"will  be  found  in  Aristotle's  Physics  and  in  the  De  anima. 
The  goal  of  all  human  activity,  the  highest  human 
good,  is  happiness,  which  consists  in  the  rational  and 
virtuous  activity  of  the  soul,  while  this  activity  has,  as 
its  natural  completion,  pleasure.  It  will  be  seen  by  this 
that  Aristotle  does  not  posit,  like  Plato,  an  abstract  ideal 
Good,  Harmony  or  Proportion,  as  the  object  of  Ethics, 
but  is  satisfied  with  the  highest  attainable  good  to  Man  ; 
that  which  all  men  implicitly  or  explicitly  recognise  as 
such,  however  much  they  may  differ  as  to  the  nature  of 
its  content.  But  in  so  far  as  this  goal  (happiness)  is  human, 
it  must  consist  not  merely  in  vegetating  or  living,  but  in 
rational  activity,  as  such.  In  accordance  with  the  animal 
and  rational  nature  of  man,  there  arise  two  classes  of  virtues ; 
on  the  one  side,  the  practical  virtues  proper,  i.e.  such  as 
consist  in  the  mastery  of  the  Reason  over   the  sensuous 


ErocH  III.]  ARISTOTLE.  73 

impulses ;  on  the  other  side  the  dianoetic  or  logical  virtues. 
Aristotle  shows  that  the  true  mean — that  rational  happi- 
ness— consists  in  the  art  of  bringing-  the  formal  or  determin- 
ing Aoyos  to  bear  on  the  material  of  impulses,  passions  and 
desires,  of  which  the  merely  natural  man  consists.  The 
capacity  of  doing  this  is  not  natural  but  human,  inasmuch 
as  it  involves  action  following  upon  reflection. 

Aristotle  is  a  pronounced  upholder  of  the  doctrine  of  free- 
wdll,  and  polemicises  in  this  character  against  both  Sokrates 
and  'Plato.  In  addition  to  the  Platonic  virtues  of  courage 
and  moderation,  Aristotle  enumerates  liberality,  magna- 
nimity, love  of  honour,  mildness,  ojDenness,  &c.,  &c.,  and 
these  are  not  as  wdth  Plato  opposed  to  one  only,  but  to 
two  extremes.  Justice  is  treated  separately  in  the  fifth 
book  of  the  Ethics,  as  the  foundation  not  only  of  all  virtues, 
but  of  all  social  life  whatever.  It  is  indeed  regarded  by 
Aristotle  as  as  much  pertaining  to  the  sphere  of  Politics 
as  of  Ethics.  In  the  sixth  book  Wisdom  is  proclaimed 
identical  with  the  highest  happiness  of  man,  being  the 
satisfaction  of  the  highest  within  him,  namely,  the 
vor5,  or  Eeason,  though  in  practical  life,  prudence  and 
reflection  are  the  more  important,  since  they  are  concerned 
wdth  the  singular. 

The  Nikomaclisean  Ethics  close  with  a  chapter  which 
serves  as  a  transition  to  the  Politics,  a  science  which 
Aristotle  regards  merely  as  the  continuation  of  Ethics. 
The  first  book  of  the  Politics  deals  with  domestic 
government,  and  affords  some  interesting  glimpses  into 
the  social  life  of  ancient  Greece.  As  the  tribe  is  con- 
stituted out  of  an  aggregation  of  families,  so  the  state 
is  constituted  out  of  an  aggregation  of  tribes.  The 
second  book  consists  in  a  criticism  of  political  theories 
(Plato's  among  others),  as  well  as  of  existing  constitutions. 
The  seventh  and  eighth  books  are  the  most  important,  as 
treating  of  the  conditions  of  the  greatest  possible  happiness 
in  a  state,  where  personal  and  civic  virtue  have  become 
identical.*    First,  Aristotle  places  the  natural  conformation 

*  The  idea  of  "  personal "  virtue  belonged  to  the  new  ethics  of 
inwardness,  of  which  Sokrates  was  the  most  prominent  exponent,  and 
was  foreign  to  the  older  ethics  of  the  ancient  world.  In  the  Politics 
Aristotle  endeavours  to  find  common  ground  for  them. 


74  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  III. 

of  the  country,  proximity  to  the  sea ;  neither  too  dense,  nor 
too  sparse  a  population.*  For  the  further  conditions  the 
constitution  of  the  state  is  responsible.  Aristotle,  while 
diverging  widely  from  the  Platonic-aristocratic  state,  is 
nevertheless  not  favourable  to  the  Greek  democracies. 
\\  hile  he  would  concede  a  large  share  of  power  to  the  middle 
class,  in  other  words  the  poorer  freemen,  which  was  as 
far  as  the  Greek  conception  of  democracy  extended,  he 
would  at  the  same  time  have  this  power  checked  by  the 
existence  of  a  sovereign. 

The  Art-philosophy  or  Esthetic  of  Aristotle  is  chiefly 
contained  in  the  Poetics,  a  work  of  which  only  frag- 
ments remain ;  but  expressions  on  the  subject  are  to  be 
found  in  the  Metaphysics,  the  Ehetoric,  and  elsewhere. 
Art  is  distinguished  from  virtue  as  creation  from  action. 
It  is  further  distinguished  from  the  creative  activity  of 
nature,  which  it  most  nearly  resembles,  by  the  fact  that  the 
artist  realises  his  end  in  another  body ;  thus  the  sculptor 
fashions  brass  into  a  statue,  while  the  plant  forms  itself, 
and  even  the  man  creates  himself,  viz.,  his  own  character. 
In  spite  of  this,  the  analogy  is  great  between  natural  and 
artistic  action.  Art  is  of  two  kinds  ;  it  may  either  be 
designed  to  complete  what  nature  has  begun,  as  to  make 
man  healthy,  to  protect  him  from  weather,  to  prepare 
food  for  his  sustenance,  to  enable  him  to  live  in  com- 
munity, &c.,  such  as,  the  arts  of  medicine,  of  architec- 
ture, of  cookery,  of  government,  or,  in  other  words,  have 
utility  for  its  end.  Or  art  may  have  for  its  end,  like 
nature,  to  create  a  world  of  its  own,  which  since  it  cannot 
be  a  real  world  must  be  a  world  of  appearance.  Art  in 
this  sense,  i.e.  art  whose  end  is  its  own  creation,  is  termed 
by  Aristotle  imitative  art,  which  clearly  proves  that  the 
distinction  between  imitation  and  originality  in  the  fine 
arts  so  familiar  to  us,  was  not  present  to  the  mind  of  the 
Stagirite.  The  sense  in  which  the-  word  imitation 
(lxiix7]TLKij)  is  used,  is  not  quite  clear,  since  Aristotle  ex- 
pressly cites  music,  the  one  we  should  regard  as  the  least 
so,  as  the  most  imitative  of  the  arts.  The  content  of  art 
(imitative)  is  the  beautiful.     Art  exhibiting  the  highest 

*  It  must  be  remembered  that  Aristotle's  reft-reuces  to  population 
only  include  the  minority  of  actual  inhabitants,  i.e.  the  free  population. 


Erocn  III.]  AEISTOTLE.  75 

end  as  accomplished  before  us,  occupies  a  midway  position 
between  theory  and  practice,  between  science  and  life ; 
inasmuch  as  the  object  of  art  is  the  particular  in  the 
universal.  In  art  individual  things  are  idealised,  not  pre- 
sented either  in  concreto  merely,  as  in  ordinary  reality,  nor 
in  ahstracto  merely,  as  in  science. 

It  remains  for  us,  before  leaving  Aristotle,  to  give  a  brief 
sketch  of  his  Organon,  or  theory  of  formal  logic,  which  we 
need  scarcely  remind  the  reader  contains  in  all  essentials 
the  completed  science  of  the  laAvs  of  formal  thinking. 
Logic,  or  Analytics  and  Dialectics,  was  to  Aristotle  merely 
the  propoedeutic  to  philosophy,  and  not,  as  with  Plato,  the 
essence  of  philosophy  itself.  The  classes  of  concepts,  and 
of  jDropositions,  answer  to  the  formal  side  of  reality.  The 
most  universal  of  existence-forms  are  substance,  quantity, 
quality,  relation,  place,  time,  situation,  possession,  activity, 
passivity.*  The  various  general  propositions  respecting 
the  real  which  are  furnished  by  these  concept-forms, 
Aristotle  terms  categories.  The  concept  is  part  of 
the  essence  of  the  real  object.  The  conclusion,  i.e.  the 
deduction  of  one  judgment  from  another,  is  divided  into 
the  syllogism  which  deduces  the  particular  and  singular 
from  the  universal,  and  induction,  which  consists  in  the 
assimilation  of  singulars  and  particulars,  and  the  con- 
struction out  of  them  of  universals.  In  the  latter  of 
course  we  leave  the  region  of  the  purely  formal ;  the 
factors  of  observation  and  experiment  coming  into  play. 
The  foremost  logical  principles  to  Aristotle  are  "  the  laws 
of  thought,"  viz.,  identity,  contradiction  and  excluded 
middle ;  which  are  immediately  cognised  through  Eeason. 
But  more  easily  (and  hence  earlier)  attainable  by  the 
human  mind  are  the  simple  notions  and  facts  directly 
conveyed  through  perceptions — the  co-ordination  and 
assimilation  of  which  constitute  induction — although  in 
themselves  the  principles  of  thought  which  this  process 
presupposes  are  prior. 

The  above  brief  and  necessarily  imperfect  sketch  will 
suffice  to  show  the  enormous  range  as  well  as  depth  of 

*  "NVe  need  scarcely  dbserve  that,  as  has  been  often  pointed  out,  this 
list  is  at  once  defective  and  redundant. 


76  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  in. 

Aristotle's  writings.  AVe  can  scarcely  wonder  at  tlie 
mediaeval  schoolmen  conferring  upon  liim  the  title  of  the 
philosopher,  so  far  does  his  work  at  once  in  character  and 
amount  surpass  that  of  his  predecessors.  For  even  Plato, 
owing  partly  to  the  strong  influence  of  the  Socratic  method, 
and  partly  to  his  natural  temperament,  left  no  Avorks  which 
could  have  served  for  ages  as  standard  treatises  on  the 
various  departments  of  philosophy,  as  did  Aristotle's  Logical 
treatises,  his  Ethics  and  his  Psychology. 

The  bibliography  of  Plato  and  Aristotle  would  fill  volumes.  The 
names  of  some  of  the  best  works  on  Plato  have  already  been  given 
(see  above,  p.  55).  For  Aristotle's  Metapliysic,  Schwegler's  Commen- 
tary is  the  best  book.  For  the  Logical  Treatises,  Prantl's  Gesckichte 
der  Logih  is  useful.  On  the  syttem  generally,  may  be  consulted  Franz 
Biese's  Die  Philosopliie  des  Arutoteles  (Vol.  II.  Berlin,  1835-18i2) ;  also 
Zeller's  Aristoteles  und  die  alte  Peripatetiker. 

The  De  Anima  has  been  excellently  translated,  with  scholarly 
introduction  and  notes,  by  Professor  Edwin  Wallace  (Clarendon 
Press.)  t 


Epoch  IV.]       THE   ACADEMICS   AND   PERIPATETICS.  77 


FOUETH  EPOCH. 

ACADEMICS  AND  PEEIPATETICS,  STOICS,  EPICUREANS 
AND  SCEPTICS. 

The  Academics  and  Peripatetics. 

This  fourtli  epocli  of  Greek  tlioiiglit  is  characterised  by 
the  elaboration  and  combination  in  various  directions  of 
the  ideas  contained  in  previous  systems.  Among  the 
Academics,  or  Platonists,  three  periods  or  "  academies  " 
are  commonly  distinguished,  the  Old  Academy,  the 
Middle  Academy,  and  the  New  Academy.  To  the  first  or 
orthodox  academy  belongs  Speusippus,  the  nephew  and 
immediate  successor  of  Plato  (347-339),  w^ho  accen- 
tuated the  pantheistic  tendencies  of  his  uncle  ;  Xenocrates 
of  Chalcedon,  who  next  filled  the  chair,  and  w^ho 
developed  the  Pythagorean  side  of  the  Platonic  philo- 
sophy;  Heraklides  of  Pontus,  the- astronomer  Philippus, 
Hermodorus,  &c.,  &c.  The  middle  academy  w^as  founded 
by  Arkesilaus  (341-315),  who  took  his  stand  on  the 
sceptical  side  of  Plato,  as  exhibited  in  the  Parmenides. 
This  soon  drifted  into  the  third  school  or  New  Academy, 
the  nominal  founder  of  which  is  Karneades,  and  where  the 
sceptical  direction  was  still  further  followed  out  with  the 
assistance  of  the  theories  of  Pyrrho.  In  Philo  of  Larissa, 
and  his  pupil  Antiochus  of  Askalon,  and  their  successors, 
who,  returning  to  a  dogmatic  standpoint,  endeavoured  to 
read  a  Stoical  tendency  into  the  writings  of  Plato,  some 
historians  have  distinguished  a  fourth  and  even  a  fifth 
Academy. 

The  Peripatetics,  as  the  successors  and  disciples  of 
Aristotle  were  called  (Theophrastus,  Gadanus,  Aristoxe- 
nus,  Dikearchus,  &c.,  &c.,)  directed  their  attention  chiefly 
to  physical  research,  and  to  popularising  the  ethical 
doctrines  of  their  master,  though  attempts  to  modify  the 
main  Aristotelian  positions  in  a  naturalistic  sense  were  not 
w^anting.  With  the  later  leaders  of  the  school,  however, 
all    such    modifications    were    abandoned,    the    text    of 


78  GEEEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IV. 

Aristotle  being  regarded  as  the  final  arbiter,  and  tbe 
elucidation  of  its  meaning  tlie  most  important,  if  not  the 
Bole  end  of  the  teacher's  function.  Hence  the  later  Peri- 
patetics are  chiefly  noteworthy  as  textual  critics  and 
grammarians.  Probably  the  most  remarkable  of  the  suc- 
cessors of  Aristotle  was  Strato  of  Lampsacus  (circa  B.C. 
288),  whose  teaching  seems  to  have  made  for  a  material- 
istic monism,  in  opposition  alike  to  the  spiritualistic 
elements  in  Aristotle's  speculation,  and  to  the  mechanical 
and  pluralistic  materialism  of  the  Atomist  schools. 

The  Stoics. 

The  Stoics,  notwithstanding  the  widely  spread  influence 
their  school  exercised  in  later  times,  cannot  be  regarded  as 
having  contributed  any  essentially  new  factor  to  the 
history  of  philosophy.  Their  ethical  doctrine  has  its 
prototype  in  Cynicism,  their  physics  in  Herakleitanism, 
and  their  logic  in  Aristotelianism.  The  founder  of  the 
Stoic  school  was  the  Cypriot  Zeno,  who  was  born  at  Kitium, 
B.C.  340.  After  a  lengthened  study  of  the  post-Sokratic 
literature  he  came  to  Athens,  where  he  was  instructed 
successively  by  the  Cynic  Krates,  the  Megaric  Stilpo,  and 
the  Academic  Polemon. 

In  opposition  to  Plato,  Aristotle,  and  even  to  Sokrates,  but 
in  full  accordance  with  the  spirit  of  the  Cynical  teaching, 
Zeno  so  far  subordinatedithe  theoretical  to  the  j)ractical,  that, 
not  content  with  defining  philosophy  as  the  art  of  virtue, 
he  sought  the  ground  of  its  division  into  Logic,  Physics,  and 
Ethics  (which  he  was  the  first  to  definitely  formulate),  in 
the  fact  of  there  being  logical,  physical,  "and  ethical  virtues  ! 
The  Logic  of  the  Stoics  falls  into  Rhetoric  or  the  art  of 
oratory,  and  Dialectic  or  the  art  of  disputation.  It  is  the 
auxiliary  of  Ethics,  inasmuch  aS  it  serves  to  enable  us  to 
guard  against  errors.  The  soul,  which  is  primarily  a  tahida 
rasa,  receives  impressions  either  from  external  objects  or 
from  changes  in  its  own  state,  through  the  repetition  and 
remembrance  of  which  an  exjDcrience  is  produced.  Hence 
the  Stoics  maintained,  in  opposition  to  Plato,  that  univer- 
sals  existed  merely  in  the  mind,  and  that  only  singulars 
were  real.     The  test  of  truth  was  the   conviction  accom- 


Erocii  IV.]  THE   STOICS.    .  79 

panying  an  experience,  whose  declaration,  when  unshak- 
able, must  be  regarded  as  final.  A  conviction  or  belief 
of  which  it  is  absolutely  impossible  for  us  to  free  our- 
selves, is  true.  This  criterion  was  called  by  the  Stoics, 
the  6p06<;  Aoyos,  and  is  identical  with  the  modern  "  ne- 
cessity of  thought."  As  a  natural  consequence  of  this 
doctrine,  follow  the  appeals  to  the  universal  consent  of 
manhinfi,  which  pervade  the  Stoic  writers.  Science  is 
merely  the  reduction  to  form  and  precision  of  the  truths 
guaranteed  by  unshakable  conviction.  Into  the  logic 
projier  of  the  Stoics  it  is  unnecessary  to  enter,  since 
it  differs  only  in  a  few  points  of  detail  from  that  of 
Aristotle. 

The  Stoic  Physics,  based  as  they  are  on  the  Herakleitan 
theory,  have  as  their  cardinal  principle  the  doctrine  of  a 
universal  animating  fiery  ether,  called  variously  Zeus, 
Soul  (TH/eu/xa),  Reason  (Aoyo?),  and  Intelligence  (vovs). 
The  contention  that  the  ultimate  form  of  all  reality  was 
spacial  and  material,  was  extended  to  the  mind  and  its 
states.  The  distinction  was  made,  however,  between  the 
finer  and  more  subtle,  the  active  and  formative,  matter, 
which  was  identified  with  the  divine  ether  or  the  world- 
soul,  and  with  the  souls  of  men  and  gods,  and  the  coarser 
merely  passive  matter  of  which  bodies  consist.  As  with 
Herakleitos,  from  the  central  creative  fire  arose  all  things, 
and  into  it  they  must  return.  The  ]Drocess  seems  to  have 
been  conceived  as  one  of  condensation  and  rarefaction. 
The  opposition  of  heat  and  cold  also  plays  a  part  in  the 
Stoic  Physics,  the  former  as  active,  the  latter  as  passive. 
The  human  soul  as  a  fragment  of  the  universal  world- 
soul  is  of  course  of  the  nature  of  fire.  The  Aristotelian 
doctrine  of  the  evolution  of  form  and  matter,  seems  to  have 
been  interwoven  with  the  physical  theory  of  the  Stoics. 
Their  Pantheism  led  up  -to  their  characteristic  fatalism, 
and  to  a  theory  of  magical  practices,  deduced  from  the 
kinship,  through  the  all-pervasive  world-soul  of  every 
portion  of  the  universe. 

The  celebrated  ethical  formula  of  the  Stoics,  that  man 
is  to  live  in  conformity  with  nature,  is  attributed  to  Zeno. 
By  Chrysippus  it  was  limited  to  living  in  conformity  with 
one's  own  nature,  and  finally  assumed  the  form  of  living 


80  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IV 

in  conformity  witli  the  divine  Eeason.  In  tlieir  interpre- 
tation of  this  doctrine  at  times  they  approached  the 
asceticism  of  the  Cynics,  though  its  crudity  was  mitigated 
by  the  high  place  they  gave  to  culture  and  meditation. 
He  is  the  "  wise  man,"  for  whom  all  outward  things  are 
superfluous,  "  who  has  that  within  "  which  renders  him 
independent  of  all  that  in  its  nature  lies  outside  his 
control ;  who  has  no  desires,  and  knows  no  envy. 

Kleanthes  followed  Zeno  as  leader  of  the  school,  but 
does  not  appear  to  have  contributed  anything  new  to  its 
doctrines.  Chrj^sippus,  his  successor,  on  the  contrary, 
was  a  voluminous  writer,  and  welded  the  system  into  a 
coherent  whole,  besides  introducing  sundry  important 
modifications.  Diogenes,  a  disciple  of  the  last-named, 
carried  Stoicism  to  Eome,  where  it  spread  rapidly.  The 
names  of  Posidonius,  the  preceptor  of  Cicero,  of  the 
emperor  Marcus  Aurelius,  and  of  the  slave  Epictetus,  will 
at  once  occur  to  the  reader  as  instances  of  Stoics  cf  the 
Eoman  period. 

That  such  a  thing  of  "  shreds  and  patches  "  as  Stoicism 
should  ever  have  attained  the  importance  it  subsequently 
did,  would  be  inexplicable  were  we  to  regard  it  as  a  philo- 
sophical system  alone,  and  forget  that  it  was  primarily 
an  ethical  movement,  and  that  its  ethics  partook  of  that 
individualist  and  introspective  character,  which  was  yearly 
growing  upon  the  world,  and  which  culminated  in  Chris- 
tianity. Stoicism  was  no  mere  system  of  phj^sics,  or  logic, 
or  ontology,  like  Platonism  or  Aristotelianism,  with  no 
very  special,  or  at  least,  a  remote  practical  bearing,  but 
a  doctrine  which  held  out  to  men  a  speculative  yet 
practical  resting-place  from  the  turmoil  of  a  public  life  in 
which  the  true  public  spirit  was  dying  out. 

The  Epicureans. 

The  founder  of  the  rival  system  to  Stoicism — Epicure- 
anism— was  born  in  Samos  B.C.  342,  and  was  thus  the 
contemporary  of  Zeno.  He  came  to  Athens  in  his 
eighteenth  year,  but  not  till  he  was  thirty-one  years  of 
age  did  he  commence  lecturing  at  Athens.  Notwith- 
standing  his   protestations  of  originality,    there   can  be 


Epoch  IV.]  THE   EPICUREANS.  81 

no  doubt  that  for  the  entire  framework  of  his  sj^sfem, 
Epiciirns  was  indebted  to  the  Atomists  and  the  Cyrenaics. 
As  with  the  Stoics,  philosophy  was  to  Epicurus  simply 
the  introduction  to  the  art  of  living.  In  the  attainment 
of  a  happy  life,  the  first  requisite  was  the  absence  of 
superstitious  fears,  and  to  this  end  philosophy  led  up. 
The  Kanonik  of  the  Epicureans,  as  they  preferred  to 
term  their  logic,  included,  as  with  the  Stoics,  a  theory  of 
perception.  From  the  senses  all  knowledge  originally 
proceeds.  Knowledge  derived  from  the  senses,  without 
the  admixture  of  any  judgment,  is  free  from  error.  It  is 
in  the  employment  of  the  understanding  that  error  arises. 
Repeated  sense  impressions  leave  in  us  the  expectancy  of 
their  future  recurrence.  (It  is  noteworthy  how  Ej^icurus 
anticipated  some  of  the  conclusions  of  modern  Empiricism.) 
That  which  coincides  -with  "  feelings,"  and  with  these 
anticipations,  is  certain  and  true.  On  questions  of  logic 
proper,  Epicurus  seems  to  have  had  little  to  say. 

In  Physics,  he  accepted  the  Atomism  of  Domokritos 
with  some  slight  modifications.  The  supernatural,  as 
embodied  in  the  popular  religion,  he  relegated  to  the 
realm  of  superbtition.  His  well-known  assertion  to  the 
effect  that  the  gods,  in  their  state  of  perfect  happiness, 
abstained  from  all  interference  with  the  affairs  of  this 
M'orld,  was  only  a  veiled  way  of  jDutting  the  agnostic 
position.  The  Epicureans  naturally  ridiculed  the  "  Provi- 
dence "and  fatalistic  Pantheism  of  the  Stoics.  The  poijular 
myths  they  seem  to  have  explained  in  an  Eiiliemeristic 
fashion.  Man,  like  every  other  being,  is  an  aggregate  of 
atoms,  the  soul  consisting  of  finer,  the  body  of  Cv)arser 
atoms.  In  either  case  dissolution  is  equivalent  to 
destruction.  "  When  death  is,  we  are  not,"  said  Ej^iourus  ; 
"  when  death  is  not,  ive  are  ;  "  whence  the  conclusion  that 
death  in  no  way  concerns  us. 

Epicurus  reduces  all  affections  to  those  of  pleasure  and 
pain.  The  thesis  that  pleasure  is  the  sole  "  good,"  is  the 
basis  of  the  Epicurean  Ethics.  Virtue  only  possesses  value 
in  so  far  as  it  leads  to  pleasure,  but  by  this  is  not  to  be 
understood  (as  with  the  Cyrenaics)  immediate  pleasure, 
but  the  greatest  sum  of  pleasure  in  the  long  run,  or 
which  is  the  same  thing  negatively  stated,  the  least  sum 


G 


/4g2'0^ 


82  GEEEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IV. 

of  pain  in  the  long  run.  This  consideration  may  some- 
times lead  us  to  a  course  of  conduct  entailing  an  amount 
of  immediate  pain,  when  this  is  the  alternative  to  a  greate-r 
amount  of  future  pain ;  and  in  the  same  way  a  present 
pleasure  may  be  foregone,  for  the  sake  of  greater  pleasure 
in  the  future.  It  is  in  the  determination  of  the  question 
as  to  what  is  the  greater  and  what  the  lesser  jDleasure  or 
pain,  that  the  philosopher  shows  his  superiority  to  the 
common  man.  Epicurus  himself  seems  to  have  regarded 
"moderation, "(coupled  with  as  much  as  possible  of  "  apathy" 
((XTra^eta),  as  the  key  to  the  solution  of  this  question. 

Among  the  immediate  followers  of  Epicurus  may  be 
cited  Metrodorus,  his  favourite  pupil,  whom  he  outlived, 
Hermarchus  of  Mitylene,  who  succeeded  him  as  teacher, 
Polystratus,  Apollodorus  (the  reputed  author  of  four 
hundred  works),  &c.,  &c.  Like  the  Stoic,  the  Epicurean 
sect  attained  considerable  proportions  in  Eome,  where  it 
was  introduced  by  Zeno  of  Sidon,  a  pupil  of  Apollodorus. 
The  celebrated  poem  of  Titus  Lucretius  Cams,  "  De 
Natura  Eerum,"  contains  the  most  complete  summary 
that  has  come  down  to  us  of  the  Epicurean  doctrine,  at 
least,  in  its  Eomanised  form.  As  regards  this  last  point 
it  must  be  remembered,  firstly,  that  the  great  successes  of 
both  Stoicism  and  Epicureanism  were  attained  after  the 
power  and  influence  of  Eome  and  Eoman  thought  were 
already  established  to  all  intents  and  purposes  throughout 
the  civilised  world ;  and,  secondly,  that  all  our  informa- 
tion respecting  them,  with  the  exception  of  a  few  frag- 
ments, comes  directly  or  indirectly  through  a  Eoman 
medium. 

In  Epicureanism  we  have  a '  more  coherent  and  self- 
contained  doctrine  than  in  Stoicism.  It  is  a  doctrine, 
moreover,  embracing  some  important  truths.  But  it  is  in 
no  sense  original.  It  established  no  new  truth  in  philo- 
sophy, nor  even  gave  rise  to  suggestions,  by  putting  old 
problems  in  new  lights.  While  Zeno  "adapted"  in  a 
slipshod  fashion  the  physical  side  of  the  philosojDhy  of 
Herakleitos  ;  Epicurus  "  adapted,"  in  a  manner  perhaps 
not  quite  so  slipshod,  but  still  rather  for  the  worse  than 
the  better,  the  physical  doctrine  of  Demokritos.  For 
their  Ethics  the  one  went  back  to  the  Cynics,  the  other  to 


Epoch  IV.]  THE  SCEPTICS.  83 

the  dyrenaics.  The  only  original  point  Epicurus  seems 
to  have  made  was  the  modification  of  the  Hedonistic 
doctrine  of  Aristippns,  from  the  advocacy  of  the  mere 
immediate  sense  gratification  to  that  of  a  calculation  of  the 
greatest  possible  sum  of  haj)piness  attainable  on  the  whole. 
It  has  been  justly  remarked  that  both  Stoicism  and 
Epicureanism  are  rather  ethical  sects  than  philosophical 
schools  proper.  The  doctrines  taught  were  put  forward 
as  dogmas  to  be  received  and  inculcated,  rather  than 
sought  to  be  demonstrated  as  propositions  to  be  heard  at 
the  bar  of  reason.  In  this  respect  they  show  a  distinct 
tendency  to  revert  to  a  pre-Sokratic  standpoint,  and  as 
such  may  be  regarded  as  the  first  symptoms  of  the  decline 
of  Greek  thought  in  the  direction  of  a  reactionary  dogma- 
tism. This  tendency  was  encountered  by  another  con- 
temporary school  or  sect,  that  of  the  Pyrrhonists,  or 
Sceptics. 

The  Sceptics. 

The  Sceptical  school  proper  has  as  its  founder  Pyrrho,  of 
Elis  (born  about  B.C.  360).  He  was  originally  a  painter, 
and  is  said  to  have  followed  the  expedition  of  Alexander 
the  Great  to  India,  where  he  conversed  with  the  Gymnoso- 
phists.  It  is  also  stated  that  he  studied  under  a  disciple 
of  Stilpo  the  Magaric,  and  also  of  a  follower  of  Demo- 
kritos.  Pyrrho  left  nothing  in  writing,  confining  him- 
self to  oral  exposition.  As  a  natural  consequence,  our 
knowledge  of  his  teaching  is  at  once  scanty  and  uncertain, 
all  that  is  really  reliable  being  confined  to  two  or  three 
propositions. 

"  He  who  would  attain  happiness,  which  is  the  object 
of  human  life,"  said  Pyrrho,  "  must  consider  the  three 
following  points :  What  is  the  nature  of  things?  What 
should  be  our  attitude  towards  them  ?  and  What  will 
be  the  consequence  of  this  attitude?"  On  the  first 
point  there  is  nothing  certain,  inasmuch  as  to  every  pro- 
position its  negative  can  be  opposed  with  equal  justice, 
since  neither  feeling  nor  reason  can  either  separately 
or  in  combination  furnish  any  safe  criterion  of  truth. 
From  this  it  follows,  as  regards  the  second  point,  that  the 
course  of  wisdom  is  to  maintain  an  attitude  of  suspense, 

G  2 


84  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IV. 

and  to  make  no  assertions  concerning  tilings.  The  answer 
to  every  question  should  accordingly  be  "I  assert  no- 
thing ;"  and  instead  of  saying  "  it  is  so,"  one  should  rather 
say  "  it  seems  so  to  me."  This  applies  as  much  to  morals 
as  to  knowledge ;  for  just  as  there  is  no  such  thing  as  an 
absolute  standard  of  truth  valid  for  all,  so  there  is  no 
such  thing  as  an  absolute  standard  of  goodness,  to  which 
universal  appeal  can  be  made.  As  to  the  third  point, 
namel}'-,  the  consequence  of  the  following  of  this  advice, 
Pyrrho  maintained  that  through  it,  and  through  it  alone, 
that  perfect  calm  and  equanimity  (aTraOela)  could  be 
acquired  which  was  the  ideal  of  the  life  of  wisdom.  '  In- 
asmuch as  the  ordinary  man  is  led  by  his  feelings  and  the 
appearances  furnished  by  his  senses,  it  is  the  business  of 
the  philosopher,  so  to  speak,  to  strip  off  the  "  man."  In 
practical  life,  however,  Pyrrho  advised  an  adhesion  to 
prevalent  usage.  The  doctrines  of  Pj^rrho  rapidly  acquired 
numerous  followers,  especially  among  the  votaries  of  the 
Asklepian  art,  but  the  school  became  subsequently  obscured 
by  the  success  of  Karneades  and  the  "  new  academy," 
which  latter  was,  nevertheless,  considerably  influenced  by 
it.  In  ancient  Greece,  as  in  modern  Europe,  the  advantages 
of  a  subsidised  chair,  and  an  "  established  position  "  could 
not  but  make  themselves  felt.  But  the  fame  of  Pyrrho 
was  vindicated  at  a  later  period  after  the  "  academy  "  had 
lapsed  into  a  reactionary  dogmatism,  when  his  sj'stem 
was  revived  with  considerable  success. 

In  Scepticism  philosophy  is  directed  to  the  same  aim  as 
in  Stoicism  and  Epicureanism,  and  we  may  add  there  is 
the  same  want  of  originality^  The  positions  of  Pyrrho, 
as  of  Arkesilaus  and  Karneades,  had  all  of  them  been 
forestalled  by  the  Sophists.  "  Scepticism  "  was  but  a  Neo- 
Sophism.  The  apparently  unconscious  resuscitation  of 
pre-Sokratic  doctrines  is  as  characteristic  of  this  period 
as  their  conscious  and  acknowledged  rehabilitation  is  of 
the  succeeding  period,  in  which,  notwithstanding,  new 
elements  are  introduced,  in  the  shape  of  Eoman  and 
oriental  influences. 

On  this  period  generally,  Zeller's  Stoics,  Epicureans,  and 
Sceptics,  msij  be  consulted.  For  Epicureanism  especially, 
see  Lange's  History  of  Materialism. 


Erocu  v.]    THE  KOMAN  AND  ANTIQUARIAN  PERIOD.        85 

FIFTH  EPOCH. 

THE  EOMAN  AND  ANTIQUARIAN  PERIOD. 

The  stagnation  of  thonght  visible  in  the  previous  period, 
that  of  the  partitioning  of  the  empire  of  Alexander  and 
the  formation  of  dynasties  by  his  generals,  gaA^e  way  to  a 
steady  retrograde  •  current  when  the  victorious  Roman 
legions  had  finally  disposed  of  the  last  vestiges  of  Greek 
independence.  The  Greek  grammarians  and  lecturers 
now  occupied  themselves  with  translating  Greek  thought 
into  the  Latin  tongue,  and  attracted  large  audiences  by 
their  exposition  of  its  doctrines.  But  philosophy  was 
becoming  emphatically  a  trade — a  profitable  profession — 
owing  to  the  new  markets  opened  for  it.  At  the  same 
time  all  that  was  required  of  the  philosopher  was  the 
statement  of  already  existing  systems.  When  the  craving 
for  novelty  was  felt,  there  were  the  old  pre-Sokratic 
systems  to  go  back  to  ;  and  finally  there  was  the  ingenious 
patchwork  of  Sjmcretism,  the  attempted  assimilation  of 
doctrines  derived  from  various  systems,  to  be  elaborated. 
New  developments  of  thought  seemed  out  of  the  question. 
It  was  enough  to  show  the  authority  of  Plato,  Aristotle, 
Zeno,  Epicurus,  and  to  interpret,  annotate  and  comment 
on  their  written  utterances.  The  three  characteristics 
of  this  emphatically  doctrinaire  period,  were  (1)  the 
establishment  of  the  four  chief  schools  as  the  recognised 
jDhilosophicial  systems ;  (2)  the  resuscitation  in  their 
original  form  and  as  systems,  of  older  doctrines  supposed 
to  have  been  long  superseded ;  and  (3)  the  harmonisation 
of  various  schools  aftected  by  the  Syncretists.  Pitter 
observes  ('  Geschichte  der  Philosophic,'  vol.  iv.  p.  35), 
*'  Although  the  leading  role  was  still  played  by  the  four 
sects,  which  had,  prior  to  this,  attained  the  greatest 
importance,  namely,  the  Academics,  Perij^atetics,  Stoics, 
and  Epicureans,  the  philosophy  of  Herakleitos,  of  the 
Pythagoreans,  of  the  Cynics  and  of  the  Sceptics  came  once 
more  into  prominence.  Of  these  the  two  last  are  the  most 
noteworthy,  inasmuch  as  the  renewal  of  the  Herakleitan 


8(5  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  V. 

doch'ine  was  very  isolated,  and  the  Neo-Pythagorean 
owed  its  significance  to  the  mystical  tendencies  of  the 
Greek-Oriental  philosophy."  In  the  present  period  the 
theatre  of  the  history  of  philosophy  is  removed  from 
Athens  and  Greece  generally  to  Alexandria  and  Eome. 
The  history  of  Greek  thought  proper,  closes  with  the 
schools  of  the  generation  succeeding  Alexander. 

The  interest  the  Eomans  took  in  philosophy  was  almost 
exclusively  ethical,  and  hence  it  was  the  ethical  side  of 
the  Greek  philosophies  to  which  they  mainly  tnrned. 
Epicureanism,  Stoicism,  Scepticism,  and  Cynicism  proved 
severally  attractive  to  the  various  orders  of  Eoman 
temperament.  The  Academics  having  somewhat  reacted 
from  the  Sceptical  tendencies  of  the  New  Academy,  it  was 
left  for  JEnesidemus  of  Gnossus,  who,  it  appears,  taught  in 
Alexandria  in  the  first  century  after  Christ,  to  revive  the 
Scepticism  of  Pyrrho,  though  its  arguments  he  used  rather 
to  establish  the  Herakleitan  position  than  in  the  sense  of 
their  author.  iEnesidemus  seems  to  have  left  a  school  of 
some  vitality  behind  him,  which  tended  to  revert  more 
and  more  to  the  Pyrrhonistic  position. 

The  physician  Sextus  Empiricus  (about  A.c.  200),  who 
was  its  most  prominent  member,  is  justly  celebrated  for 
his  remarkable  work  entitled  '  Pj^rrhonistic  Hypotyposes,' 
also  that  directed  "  against  the  mathematicians,"  in  which 
the  Empirical-sceptical  position  is  put  with  remarkable 
clearness  and  force.  The  style  of  Sextus  Empiricus  has  a 
terseness  not  usual  with  ancient  writers.  Among  the 
other  members  of  the  Empirical  or  Sceptical  school  may  be 
mentioned  Agrippa  Saturninus  (who  must  not  be  con- 
founded Avith  the  Gnostic  of  that  name),  the  pupil  of 
Sextus,  and  Favorinus,  the  preceptor  of  Aulus  Gellius. 
These  later  Sceptics  put  forward  the  following  five  argu- 
ments in  favour  of  susjDcnse :  (1)  The  discrepancy  of 
opinions  concerning  the  same  objects  ;  (2)  The  progression 
or  regression  ad  wjinitum  of  the  series  of  proofs  required 
to  establish  any  given  proposition ;  (3)  The  relativity  of  all 
things,  since  everything  appears  diiferently  in  different 
connections  and  to  difterent  persons;  (4)  The  arbitrary 
nature  of  fundamental  propositions,  the  dogmatist  in 
order  to  escape  the  regressus  to  infinity  of  demonstrations, 


Erocii  v.]   THE   ROMAN   AND   ANTIQUARIAN  PERIOD.     87 

seeking  refuge  in  certain  ultimate  propositions  which  he 
assumes  without  demonstration ;  and  (5)  The  diallele, 
namely,  that  that  upon  which  the  proof  rests,  itself  requires 
proof.  This  is  obviously  only  a  restatement  in  another 
form  of  the  second  of  the  five  arguments.  8extus  brings 
forward  a  number  of  propositions  to  prove  that  all 
demonstration  is  in  its  nature  tainted  with  fallacy,  inas- 
much as  it  must  necessarily  move  in  a  circle  ;  he  also 
anticipates  Hume  in  his  attacks  on  causality.  The  then 
current  theological  conceptions,  as  well  as  the  theories  of 
the  Stoics  on  Providence,  are  also  severely  handled  by  him. 

Of  the  earlier  Syncretist  schools,  that  of  the  Sextians, 
which  flourished  in  the  early  part  of  the  first  century  in 
Eome,  and  had  considerable  influence,  seems  to  have  been 
a  compound  of  Pythagoreanism,  Cynicism,  and  Stoicism. 
But  little  is  known  of  the  tenets  of  this  school,  and  next 
to  nothing  of  its  founder,  Sextius.  Seneca  asserts  it  to 
have  collapsed  very  soon,  in  spite  of  its  brilliant  opening. 

The  most  celebrated,  as  the  most  voluminous  Latin 
writer  on  philoso^Dhical  subjects  (who  belongs,  however,* 
to  a  somewhat  earlier  date)  was  Marcus  Tullius  Cicero 
(b.c.  106  to  43),  who  may  be  described  as  a  disciple  of  the 
New  Academy  tinged  with  eclecticism.  His  works  con- 
tain a  mine  of  information  concerning  the  philosophical 
views  current  in  his  time  as  well  as  the  manners  and 
customs  of  the  last  age  of  the  Eepublic.  In  the  '  De 
Divinatione,'  Cicero,  in  characterising  the  various  objects 
of  his  own  works,  states  that  the  '  Hortensius '  was 
designed  to  exhort  to  the  study  of  j)hilosophy ;  the 
'  Academics  '  to  show  the  most  logical  and  elegant  manner 
of  philosophising,  namely,  that  of  the  New  Academy ;  the 
*  De  Finibus  '  to  investigate  the  foundation  of  ethics ;  and 
the  '  Qua3stiones  Tusculana?,'  which  may  be  considered  a 
sequel  thereto,  to  treat  of  the  conditions  of  happiness  ;  the 
'  De  Natura  Deorum,'  '  De  Divinatione,'  and  '  De  Fato,' 
which  deal  with  the  attitude  of  philosophy  towards  the 
popular  beliefs,  being  designed  to  conclude  the  series. 
Among  the  Eoman  Epicureans  Lucretius  towers  supreme, 
both  as  regards  literary  merit  and  philosophical  insight. 
Stoicism,  on  the  other  hand,  can  boast  several  exponents 
of  the  first  rank.     Seneca,  Epictetus,  and  Marcus  Aurelius 


88  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  V. 

all  professed  the  Stoic  creed,  and  all  left  important  literary 
monnments  behind  them. 

It  would  be  useless  to  enumerate  the  obscure  gram- 
marians who  attempted  to  resuscitate  the  various  older 
systems.  As  a  transition  to  our  next  epoch,  in  which  the 
intellect  of  the  classical  world  makes  one  gigantic  effort 
to  acquire  new  life  and  vigour  by  the  absorption  of  Ori- 
ental thought,  we  may  briefly  allude  to  the  Neo-Pythago* 
rean  school,  which  arose  in  the  first  century  before  Christ, 
its  founder  being,  according  to  Cicero,  one  Nigidius 
Figulus.  Sextus  Clodius,  the  preceptor  of  Mark  Anthony, 
apparently  belonged  to  this  school.  Its  most  celebrated 
representative  was,  liowever,  the  celebrated  Apollonius  of 
Tyana,  who  imitated  the  life  of  Pythagoras,  and  achieved 
enormous  reputation  for  miracle-working. 

Men's  faces  were  now  definitely  set  towards  the  past. 
It  was  becoming  an  undisputed  axiom  with  all  thinkers 
that  the  whole  of  wisdom,  the  key  to  the  great  secret,  was 
to  be  found  in  the  literature  and  oracles  of  past  ages ;  the 
task  of  the  philosopher  was  henceforward  to  seek  it  out, 
to  pierce  through  the  language  in  which  it  was  hidden 
and  the  ceremonies  which  were  sujiposed  to  shadow  it 
forth.  In  a  word,  it  was  a  kind  of  philosophical  alchemy 
which  was  practised,  the  aim  of  the  philosopher  being  to 
transmute  the  baser  elements  in  all  systems,  creeds,  and 
formulas  into  the  pure  ore  of  esoteric  truth, 


Epoch  VL]  NEO-PLATONISM.  89 

SIXTH  EPOCH. 

NEO-PLATONISM. 

This  last  epoch  of  ancient  philosophy  is  characterised  by 
the  fusion  of  Greek  and  Oriental  thought.  Its  seat  was 
Alexandria,  the  meeting- place  of  Europe  and  Asia. 
Founded  by  the  great  conqueror  who  had  broken  down 
the  barriers  betAveen  the  European  and  Oriental  worlds, 
had  thrown  open  the  mysteries  of  Egypt,  Syria,  Persia, 
and  India,  it  had  by  the  Christian  era  become  the  second 
city  of  the  world.  Traders  of  all  nations  met  in  its  busy 
streets  and  markets ;  scholars  of  all  nations  in  its  library 
and  lecture  halls.  Alexandria  was  the  emporium  for  the 
exchange  of  goods  between  East  and  West,  and  not  less 
for  the  interchange  of  ideas  between  East,  and  West.  A 
crowd  of  grammarians,  philosophers,  and  men  of  learned 
leisure  thronged  the  city  of  the  Delta  about  the  Christian 
era,  all  of  them  aifected  more  or  less  in  their  habits  of 
thought  by  the  cosmopolitan  atmosphere  around  them  ; 
some  finding  in  the  older  literatures,  newly  opened  up  to 
them,  anticipations  of  Pythagorean  tenets,  others  dis- 
covering that  the  wisdom  of  the  East  had  been  revealed 
to  the  Greeks  in  the  person  of  Plato,  others  again  in 
Herakleitos. 

Amid  these  thinkers  and  wi'iters  was  a  Jew  named  Philo, 
one  of  the  considerable  colony  which  the  tolerance  of  the 
Ptolemies  had  induced  to  leave  their  own  land  and  take 
up  their  residence  in  lower  Egypt.  Philo,  of  whose  life 
we  know  little,  was  the  leading  representative  of  a  school 
of  thought  prevalent  among  the  learned  Jews  of  this 
colony,  which  sought  to  combine  Judaistic  theology  with 
Platonic  philosophj^.  The  writings  of  Philo  have  been 
transmitted  intact,  and  are  of  considerable  interest  in 
throwing  light  on  the  thought  of  the  period.  The  ten- 
dency of  Oriential  speculation  is  seen  to  be  just  as  much  to 
absorb  the  Greek  as  the  tendency  of  Greek  thought  was  to 
absorb  the  Oriental.  Thus  in  the  non-canonical,  or  so-called 
apocryphal  books  of  the  Old  Testament,  there  are  unmis-' 


90  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  VI. 

takable  indications  of  this  tendency;  indeed  a  similar 
leaning  is  discoverable  even  in  the  later  canonical  books 
themselves.  There  was  a  growing  anxiety,  too,  among> 
the  Jews  to  show  that  all  Greek  wisdom  was  implicitly 
contained  in  their  own  Hebrew  writings.  The  Therapeutas 
absorbed  much  of  the  P^^thagorean  doctrine.  The  Essenes 
were  also,  in  all  probability,  strongly  leavened  with 
Hellenism.  Perhaps  one  of  the  most  remarkable  phe- 
nomena of  this  time  is  the  appearance  of  pseudo-works 
by  semi-mythical  personages  purporting  to  be  of  prodigious 
antiquity.  Of  this  nature  are  the  writings  attributed  to 
the  ancient  prophet,  priest,  and  king,  Hermes  Trismegistos. 

In  Philo  himself  we  find  the  tendency  of  the  epoch  con- 
centrated, and  in  him  we  have  the  germ  of  the  system 
known  as  Neo-Platonism,  which  played  so  momentous  a 
part  in  the  final  struggle  of  the  old  Pagan  civilisation  with 
Christianity.  According  to  Philo  the  senses  and  reason 
are  alike  untrustworthy  ;  the  highest  truth  ultimately  rests 
on  an  internal  illumination  or  revelation,  in  respect  of  which 
the  human  reason  is  passive.  "  God  "  is  absolute  being, 
in  whom  there  is  neither  quality,  quantity,  nor  relation. 
"  God  "  is  not  the  creator  of  matter,  but  is  removed  from  it 
by  the  Xoyos  yei/iKooraros  which  is  equivalent  to  the 
supreme  idea  of  Plato  and  the  prime  mover  of  Aristotle, 
and  which  may  be  regarded  as  containing  implicitly  the 
sum  total  of  all  the  forms  or  ideas  of  the  real  world.  The 
relation  of  the  Logos,  or  supreme  idea,  to  the  inconceivable 
"  God,"  or  "  One,"  is  that  of  emanation,  just  as  the  material 
world  is  in  its  turn  an  emanation  from  the  Logos.  The 
world  is  often  spoken  of  by  Philo  in  similar  language  to 
that  of  Plato  as  the  "  only  begotten  son  of  God."  But  in 
Philo  everything  is  personified  and  brought  into  connection 
with  the  Judaic  theology  and  angelology  of  his  time.  The 
world  he  conceived  as  actually  created  by  inferior  beings 
— angels  and  demons — which  may  be  taken  as  answering 
to  personified  ideas  or  class-names.  Philo  illustrates 
his  doctrine  by  the  metaphor  of  rays  of  light  spreading 
from  an  effulgent  centre,  and  decreasing  in  brilliancy 
as  they  reach  the  circumference. 

The  characteristic  of  the  school  of  which  Philo  may  be 
considered  as  the  forerunner,  and  which  was  the  last  effort 


Ei'OCH  VL]  NEO-rLATONISM.  91 

of  ancient  tlionght,  lay  in  the  fact  that  in  it  human 
reason  fell  into  the  background  as  insufficient  to  the 
attainment  of  the  highest  truth.  The  "  dialectic,"  which 
for  Plato  was  the  great  and  only  highway  to  supreme 
wisdom,  became  subordinate  with  the  Neo-Platonists  to  the 
passive  "  contemplation  "  which  to  them  was  alone  adapted 
for  the  contemplation  of  the  divine.  The  science  of  the 
Greek  world  had  to  yield  to  the  mysticism  of  Asia.  This 
transformation  of  philosophy  into  theosophy,  is  the  key- 
note of  the  wdiole  Neo-Platonic  movement ;  in  some  of  its 
representatives  it  may  be  more  pronounced,  in  others  more 
veiled,  but  it  is  always  present.  Neo-Platonism  claimed 
to  be  not  only  the  reconciler  of  philosophical  systems,  but 
of  the  diverse  religious  cults  of  the  ancient  world.  It  took 
all  philosophies  and  all  religions  under  its  wing.  It 
remains  to  trace  briefly  the  career  of  this  remarkable  and 
unique  religio-philosophic  movement,  which  not  only 
furnishes  the  material  for  the  concluding  chapter  in  the 
history  of  the  ancient  world,  but  by  leaving  its  impress  on 
its  great  rival  and  antagonist,  Christianity,  has  indirectly 
influenced  the  speculative  thought  of  the  ages  which  have 
succeeded.  As  we  have  already  seen,  ever  since  Greek 
philosophy  ceased  to  be  speculatively  productive  in  the 
generation  succeeding  Alexander  the  Great,  and  began  to 
confine  itself  to  reproducing  and  piecing  together  older 
doctrines,  a  change  came  alike  over  the  object  of  philosophy 
and  the  object  of  life.  Knowledge  of  the  great  world- 
secret  was  no  longer  sought  after  for  its  own  sake,  but  as 
a  guide  to  life.  It  was  no  longer  the  welfare  of  the  city, 
or  commonwealth,  that  concerned  the  philosopher,  but  his 
owTi  individual  welfare. 

It  is  true  Sokrates  was,  so  far  as  philosophy  was  con- 
cerned, the  father  of  introspection  and  individualism,  but 
the  time  of  its  triumph  had  not  yet  come.  His  great 
successors,  Plato  and  Aristotle,  found  no  perfect  virtue 
and  no  perfect  life  save  in  the  community.  The  end  of 
all  virtue  was  still  with  them,  the  welfare  of  the  "  city." 
The  individual  by  himself  was  nothing  but  an  element  in 
the  whole.  Such  was  the  original  view  of  all  ancient 
peoples,  and  not  least  of  the  Greeks.  The  beliefs  and  cere- 
monials of  the  ancient  religions  all  tended  to  this  concep- 


92  GREEK   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  VL 

tion  of  life.  But  as  it  declined,  the  antithetic  conception 
of  the  import  of  the  individual  qua  individual,  grew.  The 
conflict  of  Sokrates  with  the  Athenians  which  resulted  in 
his  condemnation  and  death,  may  be  viewed  as  the  first 
episode  in  the  struggle  of  the  new  individualist  ethics  with 
the  ancient  social  ethics.  In  philosophy  proper,  the  success 
of  the  Stoic  and  Epicurean  schools  may  be  taken  as 
indicating  the  beginning  of  its  supremacy.  The  con- 
solidation of  the  Eoman  empire,  and  the  extinction  of  the 
free  states  of  Antiquity,  deprived  men  of  even  the  interest 
they  had  left  in  public  life,  and  threw  them  more  than 
ever  back  upon  themselves.  Soon  after  this,  a  movement 
originating  in  Palestine,  where  these  ethics  of  "  inward- 
ness "had  attained  their  highest  development,  spread  over 
the  empire,  attracting  men  and  women  of  all  conditions  in 
life,  in  a  manner  and  to  an  extent,  none  of  the  philoso- 
phical sects  could  have  ever  done.  The  whole  history 
of  the  struggle  of  Neo-Platonism  with  Christianity,  is  the 
history  of  an  effort  to  reconcile  the  introspective  move- 
ment with  the  existent  speculative  basis ;  to  satisfy  the 
new  individualist  cravings  without  the  definite  break  with 
tradition  which  Christianity  involved.  As  such,  Neo- 
Platonism  naturally  borrowed  much  from  the  ethical  side 
of  Christianity,  but  not  without  furnishing  Christianity 
in  return  with  a  groundwork  for  its  theology. 

Neo-Platonism*  practically  dates  from  Philo,  but  during 
the  first  and  second  centuries  its  development  is  obscure. 
It  is  not  till  the  beginning  of  the  third  century  that  we 
are  confronted  with  a  definite  ^personality  (if  we  except 
the  Syrian  Numenius,  who  flourished  at  the  time  of  the 
Antonines)  in  Ammonius  Saccas,  who  died  in  the  year  243. 
Ammonius,  though  the  nominal  founder  of  the  system, 
himself  wrote  nothing,  and  it  is  said,  exacted  a  pledge  of 
secrecy  from  his  disciples,  which  it  is  doubtful  if  any  of 
them  kept. 

Plotinus  (born  205),  his  most  famous  pupil  and  the 
typical  representative  of  Keo-Platonism,  was,  on  the  other 

*  The  term  Neo-Platonism,  though  its  connotation  may  be  under- 
stood by  all  students,  is  too  narrow  to  indicate  the  great  syntlietic 
movement  of  Philosi»pliical  Paganism  which  occupied  the  first  four 
centuries  of  the  Christian  era. 


Erocn  VI.]  NEO-PLATONISM.  93 

hand,  a  voluminous  writer.  The  doctrine  of  Plotinus  may 
be  briefly  epitomised  thus  : — The  highest  truth,  knowledge, 
or  Avisdom,  is  only  to  be  a2:)preliended  by  intuition,  the 
highest  grade  of  which  is  identity  with  the  known — 
wherein  the  distinction  between  being  and  knowing  is 
abolished.  The  highest  principle  is  absolute  and  uncon- 
ditioned. The  "  One,"  the  '.'  Existent,"  the  "  first  God," 
are  the  various  names  which  Plotinus  employs  to  exjoress 
this  primal  fact,  in  which  all  things  "  live  and  move  and 
have  their  being,"  but  which  is  nevertheless,  itself  out 
of  all  direct  relation  to  the  real  world.  But  how  can 
the  real  world  be  deduced  from  such  a  principle  as  this  ? 
Plotinus  replies,  by  a  process  of  emanation.  From 
the  first  principle,  namely,  is  eternally  and  necessarily 
generated  a  second,  the  content  of  which  is  less  than 
the  first;  in  other  words,  which  is  a  weakening,  a  de- 
terioration (so  to  speak),  of  its  essence.  This  stage  in 
the  degradation  of  the  primal  entity,  is  the  vov<5  or 
intelligent  principle,  which  has  as  its  final  aim  and  goal 
the  Absolute,  whence  it  emanates.  Whereas,  of  the  first 
principle  none  of  the  categories  of  reality  could  be  pre- 
dicated, the  vov<5,  or  second  principle,  may  be  said  to  unite 
within  itself  all  contradictions,  as  the  one  and  the  many, 
rest  and  motion,  the  act  of  thinking  and  the  object 
thought.  The  vovs  thus  becomes  the  sum -total  of  all  ideas 
and  general  terms,  from  the  highest  to  the  lowest.  The 
third  principle,  or  lujjpostasis  (the  term  by  which  these 
successive  momenta  of  the  emanation  are  commonly 
described),  is  the  i//i^x^,  the  universal  principle  of  life  and 
motion,  or  the  world-soul,  which  is  in  its  turn  a  weaken- 
ing, an  inferior  copy  of  the  i/oi)?,  from  which  it  immediately 
derives  the  degree  of  existence  it  possesses.  As  the  mere 
refle:^  and  shadow  of  the  rational  principle,  though  it 
acts  and  orders  the  world  in  accordance  with  reason,  it 
does  so  not  by  virtue  of  its  own  inherent  intelligence,  but 
by  that  of  the  source  whence  it  emanates.  Hence  it  is, 
that  thought  is  embodied  in  all  the  processes  of  nature, 
these  processes  simply  indicating  the  presence  of  the  ideas 
which  are  planted  by  the  vovs,  and  which  the  xl/vxq 
mechanically  translates  into  sensible  reality.  Plotinus  in 
some  places  speaks  of  the  world-soul  as  dual — i.e.,  of  a 


94  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  VI. 

soul  tending  to  matter,  which  he  designates  ^vo-t?,  and  of 
a  soul  tending  to  Eeason,  for  which  the  term  i//vx^  ^^  ^P®' 
cially  reserved.  These  three  hypostases ;  the  Trpojros  ^eos  or 
primal  principle,  the  vovs  (Reason)  or  secondary  principle, 
and  the  if/vxr/  (World-soul)  or  tertiary  principle,  consti- 
tute the  so-called  Alexandrian  trinity.  It  may  be  viewed 
as  compounded  of  the  "  Good  "  of  Plato,  the  "  Reason  "  of 
Aristotle,  and  the  Zeus  or  universal  life  of  Herakleitos 
and  the  Stoics.  This  Neo-Platonic,  ontological,  trinity  is 
distinguished  from  the  Christian,  ^/^eoZo^z'ca^,  trinity,  by  its 
being  essentially  an  immanent  as  opposed  to  a  transcend- 
ent conception  of  the  universe,  its  momenta  being,  not 
persons  but  aspects,  and  more  definitely  by  the  notion 
of  necessary  emanation  as  opposed  to  that  of  arbitrary 
creation.  The  "  Matter  "  of  Plotinus,  which  he  ojDposes  to 
"  God,"  was  not  corporeal  substance,  for  this,  in  so  far  as 
it  is  real  possesses  form,  and  in  so  far  as  it  is  i?iformed,  par- 
takes of  the  nature  of  the  vovs,  but  like  the  non-existent 
sense-world  of  Plato,  or  the  -rrpojTY]  vXtj  (first  matter)  of 
Aristotle,  it  was  a  mere  formless  negation — the  negation 
of  the  rational — as  darkness  is  the  negation  of  light.  We 
shall  understand  the  root-idea  of  the  whole  Neo-Platonic 
ethic,  when  we  remember  that  it  is  essentially  based  on  the 
notion  of  disengaging  the  w^orld-soul  from  the  non-exis- 
tent element,  the  matter,  on  which  it  acts,  and  of  which 
activity  the  sense-world  is  the  result.  The  stage  of  the 
Reason  is  then  reached,  and  lastly  that  of  the  Primal  One 
itself.  This  ecstasy,  or  absorption  in  absolute  unity 
without  difference,  motion,  or  change,  was  the  aim  of  the 
philosopher's  life. 

Plotinus  was  followed  by  his  pupil  Porphyry,  who 
represents  the  Roman  Neo-Platonism,  in  which  the 
tendency  to  theosophy  and  mysticism  was  less  marked 
than  in  the  Syrian  Neo-Platonism  represented  by  Jam- 
blichos.  Porphyry  wrote  several  w^orks  against  Christi- 
anity, which  were  subsequently  burnt.  The  allegorisa- 
tion  of  the  Pagan  myths  and  ceremonies  occupied  an  ever 
larger  place  in  the  teaching  of  Keo-Platonism  in  jDro- 
portion  as  the  power  of  Christianity  grew.  From  the  end 
of  the  third  century  all  trace  of  the  division  of  sects  is 
lost,  every  Pagan  thinker  succumbing  to  the  prevailing 


Epoch  VI.]  NEO-PLATONISM.  95 

eclecticism,  and  being  classed  as  a  Neo-Platonist.  Com- 
mentating on  the  works  of  Plato  and  Aristotle  became 
now  the  main  occupation  of  the  philosopher. 

After  the  death  of  Hypatia,  which  took  place  in  the  fifth 
century,  philosophy  was  driven  from  Alexandria,  and 
strangely  enongh  its  last  place  of  refuge  was  Athens.  It 
was  here  that  Proklos,  the  last  eminent  representative  of 
ancient  philosophy,  taught.  Proklos  was  born  a.c.  412, 
at  Byzantium.  He  studied  under  various  teachers,  and 
early  devoted  himself  to  Plato.  In  Proklos  the  religious 
side  of  Neo-Platonism  culminated.  He  had  himself  been 
initiated  into  every  Pagan  mystery  within  his  reach,  and 
was  proud  of  the  title  of  hierophant  of  all  religions. 
Christianity  alone  he  held  in  abhorrence.  In  philosophy, 
Proklos  approached  the  Syrian  Neo-Platonism  of  Jambli- 
chos  rather  than  that  of  Plotinus.  The  primal  principle 
was  with  Proklos,  itself  threefold.  From  this  triadio 
principle  the  others  emanated.  The  relation  is  invariably 
that  what  the  first  is  the  second  has  as  predicate.  Being, 
as  the  predicate  of  all  things,  stands  above  and  before  all  ; 
but  inasmuch  as  reason  (j/ovs)  implies  life  as  well  as 
being,  the  second  hypostasis  is  not  reason  (vovs)  but 
life  {^oiiji).  From  this  latter  emanates  the  reason,  which 
thus  forms  the  third  hypostasis.  Each  hypostasis  like 
the  first  is  triply  articulated.  These  three  triads  con- 
tain the  complex  of  all  reality.  The  first  is  identified 
with  the  divine  world,  the  second  with  the  demonic  world, 
the  third  with  the  world  of  human  spirits.  The  physical 
doctrine  of  Proklos  differs  in  little  from  that  of  Plotinus. 
The  Platonic  division  of  temporal,  sempiternal  and  eternal, 
is  retained  and  made  to  correspond  with  the  division  of 
somatic,  psychical,  and  pneumatic.  The  first  is  under 
the  dominion  of  Fate,  the  last  under  that  of  Providence. 
Of  the  Ethic  of  Proklos  there  is  not  much  that  is  new  to 
be  said.  The  end  of  life  was  to  him  as  to  other  Neo- 
Platonists,  the  comprehension  of,  or  union  with,  the 
divine  principle.  Immediate  inspiration  or  ecstasy  was 
the  highest  source  of  knowledge.  For  this  truth,  the  soul 
may  be  prepared,  however,  by  ceremonies  and  magical 
practices.  But  Proklos,  although  in  a  sense  a  follower  of 
Jamblichos,  was  distinguished  from  him  by  his  devotion  to 


96  GREEK  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  VI. 

all  the  great  Greek  thinkers,  who,  he  contended,  differed 
only  in  form  from  each  other,  but  whose  teaching  was 
substantially  identical — though  Plato  was  the  culminating 
point.  Proklos  died  towards  the  end  of  the  fifth  century 
(485)  at  an  advanced  age. 

He  was  succeeded  in  the  chair  at  Athens  by  his  bio- 
grapher, Marines  of  Sichem  ;  he  in  his  turn  appears  to  have 
been  followed  by  Isidore  of  Alexandria,  both  mere  gram- 
marians of  no  original  ability.  Damascius  of  Damascus 
was  the  last  professional  philosopher  of  Greece.  In  529 
the  schools  were  closed  by  edict  of  Justinian,  and  Damas- 
cius with  six  friends  banished  the  empire.  They  repaired 
to  the  court  of  Chosroes,  the  King  of  Persia,  where  they 
hoped  to  find  the  opportunity  of  establishing  a  Platonic 
republic,  but  returned  disappointed ;  Chosroes,  in  his 
treaty  with  Justinian,  stipulating  that  they  should  live 
and  die  in  peace. 

About  this  time  lived  the  senator  Boethius,  the  last 
surviving  representative  of  philosophy  in  Eome,  who 
was  executed  on  a  false  charge  by  the  Gothic  king 
Theodoric.  He  is  notable  as  occupj^ng  a  position  apart 
from  the  dying  Keo-Platonism  of  the  age,  having  helped 
to  lay  the  foundation  of  the  Aristotelian  supremacy  of 
centuries  later.  For  although  they  produced  no  effect 
whatever  on  the  age  in  which  he  lived,  his  works  were 
counted  among  the  chief  text  books  of  the  mediasval 
schools,  and  contributed  largely  in  the  formation  of  the 
Scholastic  philoso]^iliy.  It  is  doubtful  whether  he  was 
Pagan  or  Christian,  though  more  probably  the  former, 
as  even  in  his  last  work,  De  Consolatione  Philosophise,  there 
is  no  allusion  to  Christianity. 

Night  was  now  fast  closing  around  the  ancient  world. 
The  old  classical  civilisation,  from  which  the  life  had  long- 
since  fled,  was  falling  to  pieces  limb  by  limb  and  shred 
by  shred.  In  the  sixth  century  its  final  dissolution  may 
be  said  to  have  taken  place.  Within  a  space  of  little  more 
than  fifty  years  occurred  the  fall  of  the  Western  empire, 
the  closing  of  the  schools  of  philosoph}^,  and  the  formal 
abolition  of  the  consuls.  The  barbarian  was  established 
as  master  throughout  the  AVestern  world,  including  Italy 
itself,  and  was  pressing  hard  on  the  confines  of  Justinian's 


NEO-PLATONISM.  97 

empire.  The  last  remains  of  Paganism  had  almost  dis- 
appeared. In  the  cities  the  temples  sacred  to  tlie  gods 
of  yore  were  re-echoing  to  the  litanies  of  priests  and 
acolytes,  while  in  the  country  they  were  silent  and 
neglected.  The  ancient  world  was  dead,  the  mediaeval 
world  as  yet  unborn.     Such  was  the  sixth  century. 

It  is  not  without  a  certain  sense  of  sadness  that  one  can 
look  back  at  this  corpse-like  world.  Neo-PJatonism  had 
succumbed  before  its  great  rival — the  rival  whose  mental 
attitude  and  spirit  it  had  practically  adopted.  It  would 
be  curious  could  we  but  transport  ourselves  to  that  age, 
and  inhale  for  a  moment  its  intellectual  and  moral  at- 
mosphere, and  understand  the  yearning  looks  cast  back 
toward  the  ancient  traditional  rites  and  faith  by  many  even 
professing  Christians  ;  to  talk  with  the  grammarian  in  his 
library ;  feeling  that  the  philosophy  it  was  his  delight  to 
study,  Plato,  Aristotle,  Pythagoras,  Herakleitos,  had  been 
but  ill  exchanged  for  the  martyrologies,  legends  of  saints, 
and  disputes  monophysite  or  monothelite  of  the  church  ;  to 
witness  the  midnight  rendez-vous  of  the  peasant,  as  the 
rites  of  some  local  cult  were  celebrated  in  secrecy  and  in 
silence  at  the  sacred  fountain,  the  traditional  grove,  or  the 
crumbling  waj^side  altar.  One  thing  that  may  be  regarded 
as  certain,  is  that  the  Christianity  of  that  age,  formulated 
and  organised  indeed,  but  as  yet  unembodied  in  any 
distinct  civilisation  of  its  own,  and  with  the  fragments  of 
Paganism,  imperfectly  assimilated,  still  clinging  to  it  in 
their  cruder  form,  was  something  radically  distinct  from 
anything  that  the  word  recalls  to  our  minds  to-day. 


(    98    ) 


TEANSITIONAL  THOUGHT. 
THE  GNOSTICS  AND  CHRISTIAN  FATHERS. 


We  must  now,  before  taking  a  final  leave  of  antiquity, 
retrace  our  steps  in  order  to  glance  briefly  at  the  course 
of  that  speculation  which  was  either  Christian,  or  at  least 
dominated  directly  by  the  Christian  idea,  and  which  thus 
forms  the  connecting  link  between  the  ancient  world  and 
the  media3val. 

The  attitude  of  Christianity,  and  that  of  all  con- 
temporary systems  having  their  source  in  the  Christian 
idea,  was  one  of  hostility  to  "  the  world."  Every  world- 
historic  idea  necessarily  enters  the  arena  of  historj^  as  the 
negation  of  the  actual  status  quo.  But  the  anti-worldli- 
ness  of  the  Christian  idea,  though  it  included  this,  went 
far  beyond  it.  In  theology  it  meant  the  appearance  of 
the  conception  of  the  su;pernatural  in  direct  contradiction 
of  the  natural ;  while  in  ethics  it  meant  the  erection  of 
individualism  in  02:)position  to  the  ancient  communism,  the 
old,  "  worldly  "  conception  of  citizenship.  In  short,  the 
aii^z-worldliness  of  Christianity  meant  o/Z^er-worldliness 
This  change  is  traceable  in  germ  as  far  back  as  the  sixth 
century  B.C.  or  even  earlier.  The  Hebrew  prophets,  the 
first  Isaiah,  Amos,  etc.,  proclaimed  the  "  gospel  of  inward- 
ness," with  the  doctrine  of  a  transcendent  god,  a  "  searcher 
of  hearts  ;  "  the  Buddha  again,  later,  preached  the  doctrine 
of  individual  salvation  in  Nirvana,  from  the  curse  of  life, 
the  world,  and  consciousness;  Pythagoras,  in  Europe, 
seems  to  have  had  a  glimpse  of  the  same  idea ;  while,  as 
we  have  already  pointed  out,  the  decline  of  the  old  civic 
or  communal  feeling  threw  men  more  and  more  back  upon 
themselves   as   individuals.     Sokrates'    "Know   thyself" 


THE    GNOSTICS   AND   CHRISTIAN   FATHERS.  90 

was  the  first  definite  expression  in  the  Greek  world  of 
this  ethic  of  individualism.  Coincidently  with  this,  and 
intimately  connected  with  it,  arose  the  tendency  to  a 
purification  of  the  divine  and  supernatural,  by  its  separa- 
tion from  the  human  and  natural.  To  the  cultured  Stoic 
of  the  later  classical  ages,  the  gods  were  exalted  farther 
above  humanity  than  they  were  to  the  cultured  Gieek 
of  the  earlier  age,  for  even  to  contemporary  popular  concep- 
tion they  were  hardly  any  longer  mere  nature-gods.  But 
in  Europe  the  movement  of  "  inwardness "  and  super- 
naturalism  obtained,  at  least  in  any  formulated  shape, 
only  among  the  educated  classes.  In  farther  Asia,  India, 
China,  and  Persia,  and  also  in  Palestine,  it  indeed  assumed 
popular  and  organised  forms,  but  in  Buddhism,  Confucian- 
ism, Zoroastrianism,  and  the  later  Judaism,  the  future 
existence  of  the  soul,  when  taught  at  all,  was  taught  in  a 
half-hearted,  and  faltering  way;  only  in  the  two  latter 
creeds,  if  even  in  them,  assuming  at  all  a  prominent 
position.  It  is  clear  that  the  spiritualist-individualist 
movement  did  not  reach  its  highest  phase  of  formulation 
or  of  organisation  in  any  of  the  faiths  mentioned.  It  first 
appeared  in  Europe  in  an  organised  and  popular  form  as 
Christianity.  In  Christianity,  for  the  first  time,  more- 
over, the  ethics  of  individualism  became  definitely  fused 
with  a  spritual  or  supernatural  theology ;  the  individual 
became  immortal,  not  in  the  vague,  metaphysical  sense  of 
Platonism  or  of  Neo-Platonism,  in  which  the  individual 
was  merged  in  the  Idea  or  the  noetic  One,  still  less  in  the 
colourless  sense  of  the  primitive  ghost,  to  which  the  goal 
of  existence  was  the  quiescence  of  respectable  interment, — 
but  immortal  as  an  individual,  pure  and  simple,  the  heir 
to  the  life  of  the  blest. 

Some  maintain  the  primordial  idea  of  Christianity  was 
that  of  the  messianic  kingdom  on  earth.  If  it  had  been 
so,  or  at  least  if  it  had  remained  so,  it  would  have  con- 
tinued what  it  was  at  first,  a  mere  Jewish  sect.  Its 
world-supremacy  was  due  to  its  being  the  complete  ex- 
pression in  an  organised  form  of  the  rising  introspective 
ethics,  in  combination  Avith  a  spiritualist  theology.  These 
ideas,  previously  put  forward  in  an  abstract  form,  and 
isolated  from  one  another,  now  became  the  living  and  real 

H  2 


100  TRANSITIONAL    THOUGHT. 

parts  of  a  complete  systepi.  The  movement  of  inward- 
ness and  mysticism  ever  progressing  in  an  unorganised 
form,  and  among  the  cultured  classes,  now  took  organised 
expression  among  the  masses. 

The  Gnostic  systems  were  the  grotesque  results  of  an 
imperfect  assimilation  of  the  new  principle  at  a  time  when 
its  formulation  was  incomplete.  The  relation  of  the 
natural  and  supernatural,  and  their  union  in  a  divine- 
human  being  was  not  as  yet  crystallised  into  the  same 
rigidity  of  dogma  that  it  was  subsequently.  This  espe- 
cially applies  to  the  earlier  period  of  Gnosticism,  when 
though  it  was,  so  to  speak,  "  in  the  air,"  it  had  not  attained 
any  definite  expression. 

The  earliest  traces  of  Gnosticism  are  discoverable  in 
the  first  generation  of  the  Church.  To  this  period  be- 
long the  Simon  ians,  whose  origin  was  attributed  to  the 
mythical  Simon  Magus ;  also  the  heresies  of  Corinth, 
Thessalonica,  etc.,  referred  to  by  St.  Paul ;  but  the  most 
noteworthy  appears  to  have  been  the  sect  founded  by  one 
Kerinthus.  They  are  all  connected  with  Christianity  by 
some  form  of  the  doctrine  of  incarnation. 

It  was  towards  the  end  of  the  first,  or  the  beginning  of 
the  second  century,  that  Gnosticism  first  attained  any  real 
importance  as  an  element  in  ecclesiastical  history.  The 
Gnostic  sects  may  be  divided  into  two  categories,  repre- 
sented respectively  by  the  Hellenic  Gnosis,  whose  home 
was  Alexandria,  and  the  Syrian  Gnosis,  whose  home  was 
Antioch.  At  least,  this  division  seems  to  have  the  most 
to  be  said  in  its  favour,  although  others  have  been  made. 
The  Alexandrian  Gnostics  were  dominated  largely  by 
Platonic,  and  Neo-Platonic  ideas,  and  the  Syrian  Gnostics 
by  the  Persian  dualism.  The  chief  representatives  of  the 
Alexandrian  or  Hellenic  Gnosis  are  Basilides,  who  taught 
about  125,  Karpokrates,  and  Valentinus  (circa  150),  who 
in  all  probability  originally  belonged  to  the  Basilidean 
school,  but  came  to  Kome,  where  he  instituted  a  sect  of 
his  own  which  attained  considerable  notoriety  and 
numerical  proportions.  He  died  in  Cyprus.  The  Valen- 
tinian  sect  boasted  many  well-known  names,  and  lingered 
on    till   far   into   the  sixth  century.     The  only  original 


THE    GNOSTICS    AND    CHRISTIAN    FATHERS.        101 

Hnostic   work   that  lias  survived  is  the  ttlcttls  c-ocfiLa  of 
Valentinus. 

Among  the  Syrian  Gnostics,  tlie  most  eminent  names  are 
its  reputed  founder,  Menander  (said  to  have  been  a  disciple 
of  Simon  Magus),  who  taught  at  Antioch  ;  Saturninus, 
Tatian  and  Bardesanes.  As  in  a  sense  belonging  to  this 
section  of  Gnostic  teachers,  though  by  many  historians 
placed  in  a  division  by  himself,  may  be  mentioned 
Marcion,  the  distinctive  feature  in  whose  teaching  was 
the  opposition  to  Judaism,  and  the  Petrine  Christianity, 
and  its  insistance  on  a  gnosticised  form  of  Paulinism. 
The  notion  of  the  utter  corruption  of  matter  may  be 
described  as  the  ground  principle  of  all  the  Gnostic 
systems.  From  the  Pleroma  or  inconceivable  and  un- 
approachable Prius  of  all  things,  "the  immeasurable," 
the  "unfathomable  abj^ss,"  proceed  seons  or  emanations, 
which  in  an  order  variously  described  in  different  systems 
terminate  in  the  sense-world.  All  the  Gnostic  principles 
from  the  highest  to  the  lowest  are  personified.  It  is  in 
the  passage  from  the  Pleroma  to  the  world  that  the  main 
distinction  of  the  various  systems  lies.  The  Alexandrian 
Gnosis  gives  it,  in  Neo-Platonic  fashion,  as  a  continuous 
progression,  matter  only  becoming  real  in  proportion  as  it  is 
infiltrated  by  some  higher  eeon.  Both  the  Syrian 
Gnostics,  on  the  other  hand,  conceived  the  process  in 
Zoroastrian  fashion,  as  the  iuA^asion  of  the  Kingdom 
of  darkness,  matter,  by  the  Kingdom  of  light,  the  system 
of  ideal  emanations  or  geons.  The  dual  principle  is  thus 
present  from  the  first  in  this  latter  case.  It  should  be 
observed  that  the  process  of  world-emanation  or  creation 
was  apparently  conceived  as  actually  historical,  that  is, 
as  taking  place  in  time  and  space.  In  Gnosticism,  Christ 
becomes  one  of  the  higher  eeons,  proceeding  from  the 
personified  ideal  Kingdom  of  light,  to  redeem  the  world. 
But  the  rank  assigned  to  him  ditfers  in  different  systems. 
In  some  the  Christ  is  merely  one  of  the  lower  angels  allied 
to  the  Demiurges,  or  immediate  creator  of  the  world, 
while  in  others  it  appears  as  intermediate  between  the 
Demiurges  and  the  Pleroma.  But  in  all  cases,  the  Christ 
is  distinguished  from  Jesus  the  son  of  jNIary,  into  whom 
it  entered.      The  Demiurgos  is  commonly  identified   by 


102  TRANSITIONAL   THOUGHT. 

the  Gnostics  with  the  god  of  the  Jews — the  Jahveh  of 
the  Okl  Testament.  But  here  again  there  is  a  clifierence 
of  view.  Thus  to  Basilides,  Yalentinus,  Karpokrates,  etc., 
he  Avas  a  fallen  angel,  whose  Kingdom  it  was  the  mission 
of  the  ajon  Christ  to  destroy  (a  view  apparently  main- 
tained by  Marcion),  while  with  Saturninus  Bardesanes 
and  others,  he  was  merely  not  "  good "  in  the  highest 
sense,  the  Christ  having  appeared  in  order  to  supersede  his 
lower  kingdom  of  mere  righteousness  by  "  goodness."  * 

Gnosticism  forms  a  strange  and  fantastic  episode  in  the 
history  of  thought.  Neither  theology  nor  ^Dhilosophy,  yet 
something  of  both,  neither  Christian  nor  Pagan,  yet  some- 
thing of  both — bizarre  in  an  age  of  prophets,  soothsayers, 
founders  of  new  cults,  and  revisers  of  old  cults — these 
curious  theosophic  systems,  originated  in  the  iirst  century, 
rose  to  importance  in  the  second,  and  died  away  practically 
in  the  third,  though  some  of  the  sects  dragged  on  an 
existence  till  the  age  of  Justinian.  Manichasanism, 
which  arose  on  their  ruins,  achieving  a  success  at  one  time 
threatening  even  to  Christianity  itself,  was  little  but 
a  modified  Zoroastrianism.  Its  reappearance  in  the 
thirteenth  century  in  a  Christianised  form,  as  Pauli- 
cianism  or  Albigensianism,  its  rapid  spread  and  as  rapid 
extinction,  though  one  of  the  most  stirring  and  re- 
markable stories  furnished  by  the  history  of  the  Middle 
Ages,  does  not  fall  within  the  scope  of  the  historian  of 
philosophj^. 

The  common  doctrine  of  the  absolute  and  inherent 
evil  of  matter,  and  of  its  separation  from  the  divine,  led 
wdth  the  Gnostics  to  strangely  pp]30site  ethical  views. 
With  some,  probably  the  majority,  it  was  the  basis  of 
an  ethic  of  rigorous  asceticism,  but  with  others,  notably 
the  Karpokratians,  the  Ophites,  and  the  Kenites,  it  as- 
sumed the  form  of  an  antinomianism,  which  regarded  all 
actions  as  indifferent,  inasmuch  as  they  all  affected  matter 
onl}^,  and  with  this  the  divine  in  man  was  in  no  way  con- 

*  In  some  sects  (e.g.  the  Ophites,  the  Kenites)  the  antipathy  to 
Judaism  was  carried  to  the  extent  of  deifviug  the  thiugs  and  person- 
ages supposed  to  be  most  obnoxious  to  the  god  of  the  Jews,  as  the 
serpent,  Cain,  &c. 


cerned.     Epi])hanes,  the  son  of  Karpokrates,  even  enjoined 
excesses  on  his  followers. 

The  subject  next  to  occupy  our  attention  is  the  move- 
ment contemporaneous  with  Gnosticism,  going  on  within 
the  Church,  in  the  persons  of  the  ancient  Fathers.  This 
movement  had  for  its  end,  at  once  to  justify  Christianity 
to  the  cultivated  mind  of  the  age,  and  to  refute  the 
Gnostic  heresies  (so-called),  the  form  of  which  was  semi- 
philosophical.  The  link  which  the  early  Fathers  thought 
the}^  discovered  between  Pagan  philosophy  and  Christian 
theology  was — Plato.  Pliilo  and  the  Keo-Platonists  had 
evolved  trinitarianism  out  of  Plato.  The  task  of  the 
"  Platonising  "  Fathers,  as  those  were  termed  who  sought 
to  mediate  between  the  speculative  opposition  of  the  old 
world  and  the  new,  was  to  endeavour  to  show  that  what 
Plato  had  dimly  foreshadowed  by  the  light  of  reason  was 
supernaturally  revealed  in  the  new  religion.  The  great 
historical  importance,  however,  of  the  early  fathers,  con- 
sists in  their  having  laid  the  foundation  of  the  cardinal 
Christian  dogmas. 

The  first  of  the  philosophic  Fathers  was  Justin,  sur- 
named  the  Martyr  (103-167).  He  had  received  an 
education  at  the  hands  of  Platonic  and  Stoic  teachers, 
and  we  may  imagine  was  of  "  good "  family.  It  was 
apparently  in  his  later  years  that  he  became  Christian. 
The  authorship  of  two  apologies  for  the  Christians,  ad- 
dressed to  the  Emperors  Antoninus  Pius  and  Marcus 
Au»relius,  are  ascribed  to  him,  as  well  as  a  dialogue  between 
himself  and  a  Jew  named  Gryphon,  and  other  pieces  of 
more  doubtful  genuineness.  In  opposition  to  the  pre- 
vailing Polytheism,  he  urged  the  impossibility  of  the 
ingenerate,  changeless  essence  from  whom  all  things 
proceed,  being  other  than  One.  At  the  same  time  he 
admits  a  measure  of  truth  in  the  writings,  and  of  goodness 
in  the  lives  of  the  ancients.  In  Sokrates  especially,  he 
sees  the  manifestation  of  the  logos,  •  a  term  he  was 
probably  the  first  to  employ  in  a  Christian  connection. 
Plato  and  Herakleitos,  no  less  than  Moses  and  Elijah, 
he  was  disposed  to  regard  as  forerunners  of  Christ,  and 
indeed  actually  applies  to  them  the   epithet  Christian. 


104:  TEANSITIONAL   THOUGHT. 

The  doctrines  of  the  fall  of  man,  freedom  of  the  will, 
hereditary  sin,  regeneration,  are  severally  expounded  on 
Platonic  and  Stoic  principles. 

Next  in  order  to  Justin  Martyr  comes  Athenagoras, 
who  also  addressed  an  apology  for  the  Christians  to 
Marcns  Anrelius,  in  which  he  seeks  to  furnish  a  philo- 
sophical basis  for  Monotheism,  maintaining  the  Polytheist 
to  be  deceived  by  demons,  and  led  by  them  into  a  con- 
fusion between  the  divine  and  natural.  In  this  Athen- 
agoras undoubtedly  touches  the  key-note  of  the  essential 
distinction  between  Pagan  naturalism  and  Christian  super- 
naturalism.  With  one  the  divine  is  immanent  in  nature, 
the  gods  are  simply  the  personified  forces  of  nature,  they 
are  the  familiar  friends  or  enemies  of  man,  like  himself 
only  more  powerful ;  to  the  other,  nature,  in  itself  dead, 
is  created,  animated  and  governed  by  the  will  of  a  trans- 
cendent deity,  differing  in  kind  and  not  in  degree  merely 
from  man  as  a  natural  being. 

Theophilus,  bishop  of  Antioch,  about  the  middle  of  the 
second  century,  wrote  a  treatise  addressed  to  a  Pagan 
friend  which  contains  the  first  distinct  enunciation  of  the 
Christian  doctrine  of  the  trinity,  though  the  conception 
of  the  Holy  Ghost  labours  under  some  ambiguity,  being 
still  partially  identified  with  the  logos.  Iren^eus,  the 
pupil  of  Polycarp  (executed  202,  at  Lyons,  of  which  city 
he  was  bishop),  was  specially  concerned  with  refuting  the 
Gnostics,  respecting  whom  he  is  one  of  our  chief  sources 
of  information.  Hippolytus  also  dealt  with  the  same 
subject  in  a  lengthy  treatise.  Minucius  Felix  defends 
Christianity  on  the  ground  of  its  ethics.  Polytheism  he 
seeks  to  explain  away  in  Euhemeristic  fashion. 

More  important  than  any  of  these  from  the  standpoint 
of  the  historian  of  philosophy  is  Clement  of  Alexandria, 
who  flourished  in  the  third  century.  His  Stromata  are 
not  only  a  mine  of  interesting  gossip  respecting  the 
earlier  Greek  thinkers,  but  one  of  the  cleverest  of  the 
patristic  attempts  to  found  Christianity  on  a  Platonic 
basis.  Clement  distinguishes  between  the  Trt'crrc?,  or  faith, 
which  is  the  root,  and  the  yv^a-is,  or  knowledge,  which  is 
the  crown  ;  the  means  to  the  attainment  of  the  latter 
being   the  understanding  {liridTy^iiri)  of  what  had   been 


THE   GNOSTICS   AND    CHRISTIAN   FATHEIIR.        105 

previously  received  by  faith.  The  true  Gnosis  is  dis- 
tinguished from  the  false,  by  the  morality  and  true 
brotherly  love  it  engenders.  The  theology  of  Clement 
issues  in  a  kind  of  Pantheism  in  which  all  life  and  activity 
is  identified  with  God.  The  Clementine  thcosophy,  as 
may  be  imagined,  shows  many  points  of  contact  both  with 
Gnosticism  and  Neo-Platonism. 

Clement's  disciple,  Origenes  (said  to  have  been  also  a 
pupil  of  Ammonius  Saccas;,  is  by  far  the  most  important 
figure  among  the  early  Fathers.  He  it  was  who  first 
made  any  serious  attempt  to  reduce  Christianity  to  the 
form  of  a  coherent  body  of  doctrine.  Carrying  out  the 
idea  of  Clement  respecting  faith  (Tricrrt?)  and  knowledge 
(yvwcns),  he  made  it  his  task  to  formulate  the  latter,  at 
the  same  time  combating  the  principles  of  the  heretical 
Gnosis,  and  acting  as  Christian  apologist  against  Paganism. 
According  to  Origen,  in  addition  to  their  literal  or  jjsijchical 
meaning,  the  Hebrew  Scriptures  have  a  pneumatic  one. 
The  initiated  may  discover  in  them  an  esoteric  significa- 
tion to  which  the  literal  is  merely  the  cloak.  Origen, 
with  the  Pythagoreans,  regards  the  limited  as  superior  to 
the  unlimited,  and  hence  assigns  a  limit  to  the  divine 
power.  In  the  doctrine  of  the  trinity,  we  notice  a 
development  on  Justin  and  Theophilus,  inasmuch  as 
Origen  fixes  the  position  of  the  second  Person,  and 
pronounces  his  generation  eternal.  The  Holy  Ghost, 
although  spoken  of  as  above  all  created  things,  occupies  a 
subordinate  and  intermediate  position.  With  Origen  all 
creation  is  eternal,  that  is,  creative  activity  has  neither 
beginning  nor  end.  Though  the  present  world  is  not 
eternal,  yet  an  infinity  of  worlds  has  preceded  this  one. 
This  is  not  intended  to  imply  the  eternity  of  matter, 
since  the  doctrine  of  creation  out  of  nothing  is  strongly 
insisted  upon.'  The  spirits  which  were  created  first 
in  order,  having  fallen,  were  assigned,  according  to  the 
degree  of  their  transgression,  various  positions  in  the 
hierarchy  of  existence,  including  human  bodies.  The 
species  subsequently  took  the  place  of  the  individual  in 
Origen's  doctrine  of  the  fall,  individual  pre-existence  being 
apparently  surrendered.  Besides  the  exoteric  or  personal 
relation  to  the  divinity,  Origen  postulated  an  esoteric  or 


106  TKANSITIONAL  THOUGHT. 

general  one,  viz.,  tliat  of  the  Cliurch  or  comnmnity  of 
saints.  Inasmuch,  as  all  creation  is  destined  to  absorption 
in  this  whole,  it  would  imply  a  failure  of  the  divine 
purpose  if  even  the  greatest  of  the  fiends  ultimately 
perished. 

In  proportion  as  the  Church  grew  as  an  organisation, 
gi'ew  the  desire  for  the  formulation  of  its  doctrines.  The 
Chiistianity  of  reminiscence  and  expectation,  of  sentiment 
and  vague  belief,  which  had  sufSced  for  the  first  century, 
failed  to  satisfy  the  second  ;  as  a  natural  result  aspirations 
began  to  crystallise  into  a  definite  system,  assimilating 
the  while  the  various  Alexandrian  and  Zoroastrian  doc- 
trines which  formed  a  portion  of  the  general  intellectual 
life  of  the  age.  By  the  second  half  of  the  third  century 
this  process  of  crystallisation  had  approached  completion. 
But  even  yet  the  line  between  heresy  and  orthodoxy  was 
drawn  in  a  comparativeh^  loose  manner,  as  is  evident  from 
the  doubtful  position  Origen  occupies  in  Church  history. 
From  this  time  forward,  however,  when  the  position  of 
the  Church  was  assured  by  its  numbers,  wealth,  and 
importance,  against  being  crushed  out  by  any  persecution 
that  might  arise,  and  when  the  purely  defensive  attitude 
became  less  and  less  necessary,  increased  attention  was 
given  to  the  codification  of  the  mass  of  dogmas  which  had 
now  grown  up,  and  to  giving  them  severallj^  increased 
precision.  The  apologetic  Fathers  now  give  place  to  the 
dogmatic,  the  link  between  them  being  supplied  by 
Origen. 

The  foundation  of  dogmatic  Christianity  was  obviously 
to  be  sought  for  in  the  doctrine  of  the  trinity.  Hence  it 
was  this  which  formed  the  main  battleground  of  the 
various  sects  and  parties  in  the  Church  from  the  begin- 
ning of  the  fourth  century  onwards.  What  relation  did 
the  historical  Jesus  bear  to  the  second  Person  in  the 
Trinity  ?  What  was  the  relation  of  the  second  Person  to 
the  first  ?  Were  the  three  Persons  co-ordinate  ?  AVas  it 
unity  or  triplicity  which  constituted  the  essence  of  the 
Godhead  ?  All  these,  and  many  subordinate  questions 
began  now  to  occupy  the  doctors  of  the  Church. 

That  the  Christian  trinitarian  doctrine  first  took  shape 
in  Alexandria — that  seething  cauldron  of  s^^eculation — 


THE   GNOSTICS   AND   CHRISTIAN   FATHERS.        107 

during  the  second  century  there  is  no  reason  to  doul)t. 
But  its  earlier  history  is  wrapped  in  obscurity.  Of  the 
nature  and  extent  of  the  intercourse  between  the  schools 
of  philosophy  and  the  leaders  of  the  Christian  Church 
in  the  Delta  city,  we  know  nothing ;  yet  that  there 
was  an  intercourse  is  evident.*  Ammonius  Saccas,  the 
reputed  founder  of  Neo-Platonism  (which  was  really 
founded  in  all  essentials  by  the  Platonic  Jew,  Philo,  in 
the  first  century  B.C.),  is  by  some  writers  alleged  to  have 
been  a  Christian,  at  least  originally,  though  it  is  evident 
that  during  the  period  of  his  activity  as  a  teacher,  he  was 
altogether  outside  the  pale  of  the  Church.  The  truth 
was  probably  that  he  took  considerable  interest  in  the 
new  system,  and  probably  visited  the  assemblies  of  the 
Christians.  He  might  even  have  had  himself  initiated, 
as  a  means  of  ascertaining  the  nature  of  the  Church's 
esoteric  doctrine.  In  any  case,  it  is  interesting  and  signifi- 
cant that  the  Christian  Origen  is  said  to  have  been  one  of 
his  pupils,  in  company  with  the  Neo-Platonists  Plotinus 
and  Herrennius.  But  whatever  may  have  been  the 
genesis  of  the  doctrine,  the  beginning  of  the  fourth  cen- 
tury found  its  definition  the  subject  mainly  occupying 
the  attention  of  the  Christian  communities.  The  Judaic 
monotheism  of  the  Sabellians,  in  which  trinitarianism  is 
reduced  to  a  shadow,  was  opposed  by  the  jDaganising 
tendency  of  Arius,  with  whom  the  logos  or  second  Person, 
was  a  created  being,  subordinate  in  nature  to  the  first. 
As  yet  the  dogma  had  not  attained  the  consistency 
requisite  for  it  as  a  fundamental  thesis  of  Christian 
theology.  The  figure  with  whom  its  final  formulation 
as  the  canon  of  orthodoxy  is  indissolubly  associated,  is 
that  of  Athanasius,  (298-373),  bishop  of  Alexandria.  On 
the  thesis  of  Athanasius  it  is  unnecessary  to  dwell,  since, 
after  a  desperate  struggle  with  Arianism,  it  obtained 
what  proved  a  decisive  victory  at  Nica3a,  in  325,  where 
it  was  erected  by  a  large  majority  into  the  orthodox 
Christian  doctrine,  a  position  it  has  maintained  through- 
out Christendom  ever  since.     The  attempts  subsequently 

*  According  to  the  critics  the  fourth  Gospel  was  the  immediate 
outcome  of  this  intercourse. 


108  TRANSITIONAL    THOUGHT. 

made  to  mediate  between  the  two  parties,  the  disputes 
about  a  word,  and  the  political,  social  and  religious  dis- 
turbances caused  by  the  question  during  the  whole  of 
the  fourth  century,  lie  entirely  outside  the  history  of 
philosoph}^ 

The  last  of  the  Church  Fathers  that  need  detain  us  is 
St.  Augustine  (353-412),  bishop  of  Hippo,  whose  specula- 
tive career  offers  many  points  of  interest,  as  connecting 
the  ancient  and  the  medigeval  world.  Of  Christian 
parentage,  Augustine  subsequently  became  Manichfean, 
but  after  a  time  reverted  to  the  creed  of  his  youth. 
Augustine  found  a  refuge  from  scepticism,  like  Descartes 
at  a  later  time,  in  the  certainty  of  self-consciousness. 
From  this  he  argues  the  certainty  of  being,  life,  and 
knowledge,  which  he  maintains  are  involved  in  the 
primary  fact  of  self-consciousness.  Reflection  on  the 
highest  stage  of  Being  shows,  he  maintains,  that  the 
reason  in  its  acts  of  cognition  and  judgment,  pre-supposes 
certain  fundamental  principles,  culminating  in  the  eternal 
truth  Avhich  unites  them  in  that  synthesis  which  is  tanta- 
mount to  the  supreme  all-embracing  idea  of  Plato  or  the 
creative  intellect  of  Aristotle,  but  which  Augustine  identi- 
fies with  the  Christian  Logos.  That  this  identification  of 
knowledge  or  consciousness  itself  with  the  divinity,  is  in- 
distinguishable from  the  Pantheism  of  the  Neo-Platonists  is 
obvious.  Indeed  Augustine  himself  admits  his  Platonism, 
often  designating  Plato  "  the  true  philosopher."  For  him 
the  distinction  between  Faith  and  Knowledge,  Eevelation 
and  Reason,  does  not  exist.  The  one  is  merely  a  prepara- 
tory stage  to  the  other.  Everywhere  faith  is  the  begin- 
ning, and  precedes  Reason,  although  intrinsically  Reason 
is  higher  than  faith.  Inasmuch  as  God  is  wisdom 
itself,  the  philosoj)her,  that  is,  the  friend  of  wisdom,  is 
the  friend  of  God.  God,  as  the  essential  object  of  all 
knowledge,  cannot  be  conceived  under  the  categories 
which  serve  to  determine  mere  objects  of  sense.  He  is 
great  without  quantity,  good  without  quality,  every- 
where present  irrespective  of  space,  eternal  apart  from 
time.  He  cannot  even  be  spoken  of  as  substance,  since 
no  accidents  can  be  predicated  of  him.  The  best  definition 
that  can  be  given  is  that  of  the  essence  of  all  things,  for 


THE   GNOSTICS   AND   CHRISTIAN   FATHERS.        109 

outside  of,  and  apart  from,  him,  nothing  exists.  Since 
his  being  knows  no  limitation,  he  is  better  defined  in 
a  uegative  than  a  positive  manner.  Being,  knowledge, 
will,  action,  are  in  him  one.  In  short,  God  is  the  unknow- 
able, absolute,  and  unconditioned  fact  which  the  known, 
the  relative,  and  the  couditioned  pre-supposes.  But  the 
character  of  Augustine  as  Christian  dogmatist  required 
that  he  should  not  stop  at  an  unknowable  God.  Hence 
he  proceeds  to  a  consideration  of  the  manifestation  of  God 
as  revealed  to  us.  This  is  nothing  other  than  the  doctrine 
of  the  trinity.  Here  again  the  agreement  with  the  Neo- 
Platonists  is  strong,  though  the  personal  terminology 
of  the  Christian  doctrine  is  formally  maintained.  Indeed 
Augustine,  so  ftir  as  the  letter  went,  actually  put  the 
coping-stone  on  the  work  of  Athanasius,  by  not  only 
distinguishing  the  Holy  Ghost  from  the  other  Persons, 
but  by  co-ordinating  it  with  the  logos  ;  his  doctrine  being 
that  in  each  of  the  three  Persons,  the  divine  substance  is 
equally  preseat 

Thus  to  non-metaphysical  ecclesiastics,  Augustine  might 
well  appear  the  champion  of  orthodoxy :  though  looked 
at  a  little  more  closely,  it  would  be  difficult  to  find  a 
single  heresy  with  which  he  might  not  be  chargeable.* 
With  all  his  verbal  adhesion  to  the  Christian  dogma,  it  is 
plain  that  philosophically  he  is,  in  spite  of  himself,  a 
Platonist  and  a  Pantheist.  The  world  is  for  him  "  der 
Gottheit  den  ewigen  Kleid."  The  creative  power  with- 
drawn, and  the  world  would  disappear.  Into  Augustine's 
theory  of  the  freedom  of  the  human  will,  which  he  identi- 
fied with  the  divine  will,  thereby  opening  a  path  to  his 
predestinarian  theology,  and  his  controversy  with  Pelagius 
on  this  head,  space  precludes  our  entering.  It  is  enough 
to  state  that  Augustine  was,  in  the  exoteric  and  practical 
side  of  his  theology,  as  much  the  type  and  embodiment  of 
the  Christian  theologian,  as  he  was  in  the  esoteric  and 
theoretical  side  of  the  Neo-Platonic  philosopher.  With 
Augustine  the  constructive  period  of  Christian  dogmatics 
finally   closes.     The   whole    Christian   scheme   was   now 

*  The  passages  in  which  Augiistine  repeatedly  insists  on  the  equal 
participation  of  the  three  Persons  in  every  creative  act,  might  have 
been  written  by  Sabellius. 


110  TRANSITIONAL   THOUGHT. 

mapped  out  in  all  its  essentials,  and  many  of  its  particn^ 
lars.  All  that  remained  was  to  apply  this  system  to  the 
details  of  life.  An f»;nstine  practically  conclndes  the  line 
of  the  ancient  Christian  Fathers,  as  his  contemporary, 
Proklos,  that  of  the  ancient  pagan  philosophers.  In 
Augustine  we  take,  as  it  were,  a  second,  and  this  time  a 
final  farewell  of  the  ancient  world.  The  curtain  falls 
once  more.  It  will  rise  again  on  a  Catholic  and  feudal 
Europe,  whjere  the  races  of  modern  times  furnish  the 
chief  actors. 

Among  the  best  works  on  the  Christian  and  semi-Christian  specula- 
tion of  the  first  three  centuries,  may  be  mentioned  :  in  English,  Smith's 
'  Dictionary  of  Christian  Sects  and  Heresies,'  Hansel's  *  Gnostics  of 
the  Second  Century,'  Article,  "  Gnosticism,"  '  Encyclopaedia  Britan- 
nica,'  9th  ed.,  also  separate  articles,  Basilides,  Carpocrates,  Cerinthus, 
&c. ;  in  French,  Matter's  '  Histoire  du  Gnosticisme ' ;  in  German, 
Baur's  'Drei  erste  Jahrhunderte  des  Christenthums,'  Neauder's 
'  Kirchengeschichte '  (also  translated  in  Bohn's  library),  and  among 
recent  works  Hilgenfeld's  '  Ketzergeschichte,'  &c.,  &c.  The  original 
works  of  the  early  Fathers  are  translated  in  the  Aute-Nicene  library. 


THE   EARLIER   SCHOOLMEN.  Ill 


MEDIiEYAL   PHILOSOPHY. 


THE  EAELIER  SCHOOLMEN. 

The  first  representative  of  mediaeval  philosophy  occupies 
80  far  as  speculation  is  concerned,  a  somewhat  anomalous 
position.  He  stands  like  a  solitary  obelisk  between  the 
ancient  world  and  the  middle  ages. 

The  rise  and  rapid  decline  of  the  pure  Keltic  civili- 
sation is  an  interesting  phenomenon  in  the  history  of 
mediaeval  Europe.  Its  greatest  architectural  monument 
remaining  is  the  cathedral  of  lona ;  its  greatest  literary 
monument,  the  works  of  Johannes  Scotus  Erigena. 
Erigena,  the  first  mediaeval  philosopher,  is  the  solitary 
representative  of  Platonism  among  the  schoolmen,  if, 
indeed,  he  can  be  properly  classed  as  a  schoolman. 

The  spirit  of  scholasticism,  or  at  least  of  the  earlier 
scholasticism,  was  one  of  subordination.  The  function  of 
the  reason  was  to  act  as  j;he  Jiandmaid  of  dogma,  in 
defining,  applying,  justifying  it ;  in  Erigena,  however,  we 
see  a  much  freer  tendency.  In  him,  Eeason  takes  prece- 
dence of  dogma,  since  even  the  f]oo;]nas  laid  down  and 
formulated  by  the  fathers,  were  arrived  at  by  the  help  of 
Eeason.  Erigena  is  fond  of  saying  that  philosophy  and 
religion  are  one,  that  true  philosophy  is  true  religion,  and 
vice  versa.  At  the  same  time,  he  proceeds  to  explain  the 
world  on  Platonic  principles,  into  which  the  Christian 
scheme  enters  only  incidentally. 

Scotus  Erigena  was  bom  in  Scotland,  or  Ireland  (it  is 
uncertain  which,  though  most  probably  the  latter),  about 
the  year  800.  He  doubtless  received  his  education  in  one 
of  the  monastic  schools  which  then  covered  Ireland  and 
Keltic  Britain,  and  where  Greek  was  still  taught  in 
conjunction  with  Latin.  In  843  he  was  called  to  the 
court  of  Charles  the  Bald  of  France,  and  entrusted  with 


112  MEDIAEVAL   PHILOSOPHY. 

the  Chair  of  the  Schola  Platina,  a  position  he  retained  foi 
many  years.  The  tradition  which  assigns  to  him  an 
academical  post  in  the  University  of  Oxford,  under  Alfied 
the  Great,  is  generally  considered  nnaiithentic.  Scotus 
Erigena,  in  all  probability,  died  in  Paris  about  the 
year  877. 

The  totality  of  all  Being  or  Xature*  falls,  according  to 
Erigena,  under  four  classes ;  the  Uncreated-Creating,  thi? 
Created-Creating,  the  Created -Uncreating,  and  the  Uncrea.- 
ting-Uncreated.  By  the  first  and  the  last  of  these  classes, 
God  in  His  pure  essence  is  indicated  ;  the  former  denoting 
God  as  the  ground  of  all  Being,  the  latter  as  the  final  end 
and  goal  of  all  things.  The  second,  which  stands  in  direct 
opposition  to  the  fourth,  as  does  the  third  to  the  first, 
comprise  between  them  the  totality  of  real  or  related 
existence.  It  may  be  remarked  that  the  first  three 
classes  are  discoverable  in  both  Plato  and  Aristotle,  not 
to  speak  of  later  thinkers,  while  the  fourth  is  plainly 
indicated  by  the  Neo- Platonic  writers.  Of  the  five  books 
into  which  the  philosophical  treatise  of  Erigena  is  divided, 
the  first  treats  of  God  as  the  Uncreated-Creating  ;  as  that 
in  and  through  which  everything  exists.  He  is  the  begin- 
ning, the  middle,  and  the  end,  and  hence,  says  Erigena, 
justly  regarded  as  the  imity  of  three  Persons.  This  trini- 
tarian  conception  may  also  be  viewed  in  another  light,  as 
theunity  of  being,  willing,  and  knowing,  or  again  of  essence, 
potentiality,  and  actuality.  The  same  trinity  is  discover- 
able in  the  soul  of  man,  the  "image  of  God,"  it  matters  not 
whether  we  adopt  the  first  of  the  classifications  just  given, 
which  was  that  of  Augustine,  or  the  second,  which  is  that  of 
the  other  Fatliers.  In  agreement  with  Augustine,  Erigena 
denies  any  of  the  categories  of  thought  to  the  essence  of 
God,  who  he  insists  can  best  be  defined  as  ^mre  nothing. 

The  first  passage  or  progression  is  to  the  subject-matter 
of  the  second  book,  which  deals  with  the  created,  which 
is  also  creating.  This  is  nothing  other  than  the  system 
of  the  Platonic  ideas,  or  ideal  prototypes,  in  other  words, 
the  logos  which  embraces  all  things  as  the  beginning,  in 

*  As  will  be  seen,  Erigena  employs  the  word  Nature  as  synony- 
mous with  Being,  and  not  in  the  usual  limited  sense,  of  the  world  as 
perceivable. 


THE   EARLIER   SCHOOLMEN.  113 

whicli  all  things  were  created,  as  the  wisdom  in  which 
they  were  intuited.  Although  created,  they  are  neverthe- 
less eternal,  inasmuch  as  the  process  of  creation  is  not  in 
time,  but  co-eval  with  time.  As  with  the  Neo-Platonists 
these  principles  stand  to  each  other  in  a  graduated  order 
of  participation.  They  Comprise  within  them  the  principles 
and  forms  of  all  real  things,  which  are  only  real  in  so  far 
as  they  participate  in  the  essence  of  these  forms.  It  is 
thus  that  they  may  he  regarded  as  the  direct  causes  and 
principles  of  the  real  world,  or  of  that  nature  which  is 
created,  but  does  not  itself  create.  This  complex  of 
indi\ddual  objects  forms  the  theme  of  the  third  book.  The 
latter  comprises  a  cosmology  with  which,  by  a  process  of 
allegorisation,  the  Biblical  is  forced  into  accordance.  Man 
is  the  officina  creaturarum,  in  whom  the  consciousness 
of  the  whole  lower  creation  is  gathered  up.  He  is 
now  out  of  paradise,  inasmuch  as  he  is  divided  from 
God  by  the  sense- world.  But  this  is  not  the  end  of  his 
being.  He  is  destined  to  a  reconciliation  with  God,  a 
reabsorption  in  the  divine  essence.  Respecting  this,  the 
fourth  and  fifth  books  treat.  In  these  the  Pantheism  of 
Erigena  is  most  pronounced. 

Evil  has  no  substantial  existence,  since  the  ground 
and  essence  of  all  reality  is  God.  Similarly  evil  has  no 
positive  cause.  It  is  incausale.  Free  will,  to  which  many 
have  referred  the  existence  of  evil,  only  determines  it- 
self to  evil,  through  want  of  knowledge,  that  is,  through 
our  mistaking  evil  for  good.  (We  call  the  attention  of 
the  reader  to  the  fact  that  this  is  an  echo  of  the  Sokratic 
doctrine.)  Since  its  object  is  a  mistaken  one,  since  it  is 
evil,  and  therefore  negation,  the  will  remains  unsatisfied, 
its  end  being  unaccomplished.  This  we  term  punishment, 
and  therefore  that  only  can  be  punished  which  does  not 
exist.  The  purpose  of  punishment  is  hence,  not  the 
destruction  of  the  substance  of  the  sinner,  but  merely 
the  accident  of  this  substance,  the  misdirected,  and  there- 
fore essentially  negative,  will.  On  this  ground  Erigena 
insists  with  Urigen  on  the  ultimate  union  of  all  things 
in  God,  on  the  reabsorption  of  the  whole  creation  into 
the  substance  from  which  it  sprang,  after  all  that  is 
evil,  i.e. J  negative   in  it,  has  been  finally  purged  away. 

I 


114  MEDIEVAL  PHILOSOPHY. 

This  re-absorption  should  logically  exclude  individuality ; 
but  Erigena  does  not  appear  to  contemplate  this,  at  least 
more  than  to  a  limited  extent.  The  antitheses  of  creator 
and  created,  heaven  and  earth,  male  and  female,  indeed 
disappear,  but  the  individuality  remains,  though  in  what 
sense  it  is  difficult  to  determine.  *As  in  the  order  of  crea- 
tion, so  in  the  order  of  absorption  or  deification,  there 
are  degrees  according  to  purity,  or  the  reverse. 

Tlie  great  work  of  Erigena,  De  Divisione  Naturse,  is 
written  in  the  form  of  a  dialogue  between  a  master  and 
disciple. 

Anselm. 

We  pass  over  a  period  of  two  hundred  years,  during 
which  no  names  of  special  note  occur  in  the  schools.  This 
brings  us  to  the  eleventh  century,  a  most  important  one 
in  the  history  of  scholasticism,  since  it  gave  birth  to  two 
of  its  most  prominent  figures,  Anselm  and  Abelard.  The 
former  was  born  in  1035  at  Aosta.  He  was  educated  first 
at  Avranches  and  subsequently  at  the  Abbaie  de  Bee  in 
Kormandy,  where  he  followed  Lanfranc  as  prior,  and 
afterwards  as  abbot.  In  the  archbishopric  of  Canterbury, 
which  he  occupied  from  1089  till  his  death  in  1099,  he 
w^as  also  a  successor  of  Lanfranc. 

With  Anselm  philosophy  becomes  avowedly  the  hand- 
maid of  theology.  Its  object  is  the  justification  of  dog- 
matics, although  its  procedure,  Anselm  declares,  must 
be  independent  of  dogma.  In  Erigena  we  saw  that  the 
idea  of  personality  and  conscious  volition  in  the  Godhead 
and  the  world-order  (the  fundamental  feature  in  all 
theology — as  such.  Christian  or  otherwise — the  feature 
which  distinguishes  it  from  metaphysic  proper),  was 
left  very  much  in  abeyance.  In  Anselm,  on  the  con- 
trary, as  might  be  expected,  it  assumes  a  much  more 
prominent  place,  since  Anselm  was  no  searcher  after 
truth,  but  a  philosophical  advocate  on  behalf  of  the  doc- 
trines of  the  Church.  His  chief  wor]'  is  the  Proslogimn^ 
which  contains  the  first  serious  attempt  i^j  ^'ase  rJieology 
on  the  so-called  ontological  argument.  Anselm  argues 
the  existence  of  God  from  the  mere  conception  of  a 
supreme  being  which  obtains  in  the  mind.      All  things, 


THE   EARLIER   SCHOOLMEN.  115 

inasmuch  as  they  can  be  expressed  by  predicates,  point  to 
this  ultimate  concept,  just  as  the  predicate  great  points 
to  the  concept  greatness,  the  predicate  good  tb  good- 
ness, &c.  Ansehn  agrees  with  Augustine  in  defining  God 
as  the  Essence  of  all  things.  In  three  dialogues  de  veri- 
tate,  de  lihero  arbitrio,  and  de  causa  diaholi,  Anselm  de- 
velopes  the  thesis  that  the  being  of  the  real  world  is  es- 
sentially negative,  and  in  this  way  explains  creation  out 
of  nothing ;  the  meaning  of  which  is  that  the  being  of  the 
world  is  the  negation  of  the  being  of  the  Deity.  Its 
purpose  is  the  glory  of  the  Deity,  to  which  even  the  fall  of 
man  has  contributed,  by  enabling  man  to  become  conscious 
of  that  glory.  The  freedom  of  the  will  is  also  dealt  with, 
in  a  libertarian  sense. 

Anselm  occupies  the  position  of  a  link  between  the 
Platonism  of  Erigena  and  his  successors,  and  the  pure 
Aristotelianism  of  the  schoolmen  proper.  The  great 
scholastic  controversy — Nominalism  versus  Eealism— was 
yet  to  come,  although  near  at  hand.  Its  immediate 
starting-point  may  be  considered  the,  in  the  first  instance, 
purely  theological  polemic  of  Anselm  against  Roscellinus, 
canon  of  Champiegne,  whose  doctrine  on  the  subject  of  the 
trinity  tended  in  the  direction  of  Tritheism.  Anselm  in 
this  dispute  takes  the  realist  position  against  Eoscellinus, 
who  is  the  representative  of  the  most  extreme  nominalism. 
The  former,  like  all  his  predecessors,  and  in  spite  of  the 
Aristotelian  tendency  of  much  of  his  own  thought,  had 
never  doubted  that  universals  were  to  be  regarded  with 
Plato  as  having  a  substantive  existence  apart  from  the 
particulars  and  singulars  in  which  they  were  realised. 
The  latter  maintained  the  then  paradoxical  (and  in  truth 
equally  one-sided)  position  that  universals  had  no  signifi- 
cance except  as  words,  that  they  were  flatus  vocis.  It  is 
noticeable  how  the  great  metaphysical  problem  which  had 
occupied  the  ancients — the  relation  of  matter  and  form — 
was  now  becoming  whilTtled  down  to  a  mere  logical  or 
even  psychological  issue,  in  which  its  kernel  was  entirely 
lost  and  its  bearings  totally  changed.  It  is  remarkable 
also  how  this  mere  question  of  the  schools  was  made  the 
arena  for  the  strife  of  Church  parties  and  the  battleground 
of  twelfth-century  orthodoxy  and  heresy.      At  first  the 

I  2 


116  .       MEDIAEVAL   PHILOSOPHY. 

weight  of  the  Church's  authority  was  thrown  into  the 
realist  scale.  This  was  to  be  expected,  not  only  owing  to 
the  heterodox  theological  attitude  of  the  first  representa- 
tive of  nominalism,  but  also  because  it  gave  to  sense-per- 
ception the  foremost  place,  besides  cutting  at  the  root  of 
the  ontological  and  all  similar  arguments.  The  panthe- 
istic tendencies  of  Eealism,  when  logically  carried  out, 
were  apparently  not  discerned  at  this  time. 

Abelard. 

The  leading  representative  of  the  great  scholastic 
controversy  was  Abelard  (born  1079),  a  native  of  Pallet, 
or  Palais,  near  Nantes.  He  studied  first  under 
Eoscellinus,  and  afterwards  in  Paris  under  the  Eealist 
William  of  Champeaux.  The  result  was  a  dissatisfaction 
with  the  teaching  of  either,  but  especially  with  that  of  the 
latter,  which  led  Abelard  to  challenge  his  master  to  a 
public  disputation.  This  ended  triumphantly  for  Abelard, 
inasmuch  as  William  was  compelled  to  a  formal  recanta- 
tion of  his  extreme  Realism.  Abelard's  reputation  as  the 
greatest  dialectician  of  the  age  now  grew  rapidly,  and 
scholars  flocked  from  all  sides  to  hear  the  PMlosojphus 
Peripateticus,  as  he  somewhat  arrogantly  styled  himself. 
Eising  higher  and  higher  in  public  estimation,  in  spite  of 
a  lengthened  remission  of  labour  owing  to  ill-health,  as 
well  as  of  the  not  unnatural  animosity  of  his  former  master 
and  now  humiliated  rival,  William  of  Champeaux,  whom 
he  had  literally  driven  from  Paris,  Abelard  attained  the 
chair  of  the  great  Cathedral  school  of  Notre-Dame,  being 
at  the  same  tiYne  nominated  canon. 

It  was  now  that  the  romantic  episode  occurred  which 
was  destined  to  overshadow  the  whole  of  Abelard's  sub- 
sequent career,  and  which  has  given  to  the  dialectician  and 
schoolman  the  undying  place  he  occupies  in  popular  im- 
agination. It  would  be  out  of  place  in  a  manual  like  the 
present,  to  enter  into  a  detailed  account  of  the  well-known 
story  of  the  seduction  of  the  canon  Fulbert's  niece  by 
Abelard,  of  Abelard's  passion,  and  Heloise's  life-long 
devotion.  A  subsequent  secret  marriage,  though  for  a 
time  it  appeased  the    indignation   of   Fulbert,  did    not 


THE    EARLIER   SCHOOLMEN.  117 

prevent  the  perpetration  of  the  crime  which,  to  a  large 
extent,  shattered  Abelard's  subsequent  life.  He  was  not 
born  fur  the  cloisters,  and  his  attempt  to  retire  from 
active  work  to  the  abbey  of  St.  Denis  was  a  failure.  He 
reapjoeared  as  teacher,  seemed  to  be  regaining  his  old 
popularity,  was  condemned  on  a  charge  of  heresy,  again 
fled  from  the  world,  this  time  into  the  wilderness,  was 
sought  out  by  the  students,  again  induced  to  teach,  was 
once  more  driven  by  new  dangers  to  the  desolate  abbey, 
Gildas  de  Rhuys,  in  Brittany,  whence  was  penned  his 
share  of  the  well-known  correspondence  with  Heluise. 
The  final  blow  to  Abelard's  reputation  was  the  fiasco  of 
his  attempt  to  answer  St.  Bernard,  to  whom  his  dialectics 
were  an  abomination.  Condemned  once  more  for  heresy, 
Abelard  was  on  his  way  to  plead  his  cause  in  person 
at  Eome  when  his  health  broke  down,  and  he  died  shortly 
after,  on  the  21st  of  April,  1142,  at  the  priory  of  St.  Marcel. 
He  was  buried  at  the  convent  of  the  Paraclete  (erected  by 
his  own  scholars),  of  which  Heloise,  who  subsequently 
shared  his  tomb,  was  Superior.  Their  bones,  after  many 
vicissitudes,  now  lie  in  Pere  la  Chaise. 

Abelard  was  in  a  sense  the  founder  of  Scholasticism, 
that  is,  the  method  of  philosophising  (for  a  system 
Scholasticism  was  not),  which  has  for  its  end  the  rational 
formulation  of  the  Church's  doctrines.  In  Abelard  we 
first  find  that  exclusive  ascendency  of  Aristotle,  which 
is  its  main  characteristic.  Plato,  before  the  chief  store- 
house for  the  philosopher  and  theologian,  henceforth 
remained  a  sealed  book  until  the  Renaissance.  It  was 
Abelard,  too,  who  fixed  the  question  of  universal s  as  the 
central  one.  In  antagonism  alike  to  the  extreme  Realism 
of  William  of  Champeaux,  and  the  extreme  Nominalism  of 
Roscellinus,  he  maintained,  formally  at  least,  the  Aristo- 
telian position,  universalia  in  rebus.  We  say  formally,  as  it 
is  doubtful  how  far  Abelard  saw  the  metajDhysical 
bearings  of  the  question.  But  at  least  he  joined  with  the 
Kominalists  in  ascribing  full  reality  only  to  sensible 
concretes,  while  he  repudiated  the  fiatus  vocis  doctrine, 
proclaiming  the  existence  of  the  universal  in  the  concrete, 
and  declaring  it  to  emerge  in  the  act  of  predication. 

The  doctrine  of  Abelard  has  been  termed  conceptualism  ; 


118  MEDIEVAL   PHILOSOPHY. 

but  the  applicability  of  this  desigTiation  rests  upon  the 
assumption  that  Abelard  concerned  himself  with  the  mere 
psychological  question  of  the  mental  subsistence  of  the 
universal.  It  is  most  probable  that  he  never  clearly 
grasped  the  distinction  between  the  metaphysical  and  the 
psychological  problems.  He  was  pre-eminently  a  logician 
who  took  delight  in  dialectical  combats  for  their  own 
sake,  as  his  contemporaries  of  the  sword  took  delight  in 
combats  with  the  lance  for  their  own  sake.  With  ethics, 
however,  Abelard  occupied  himself  to  some  extent,  and 
some  of  his  observations  in  this  department  are  acute,  and 
in  certain  points  even  anticipate  the  remarks  of  modern 
thinkers,  although  awe  of  the  Church's  authority  pre- 
vented him  from  treating  the  subject  in  any  thorough 
manner. 


THE  AKABIANS  AND  JEWS.  119 


THE  AEABIANS  AND  JEWS. 

We  must  turn  aside  now  from  the  Schools  of  Catholic 
Europe,  with  the  controversy  raging  between  Nominalism 
and  Eealism,  where  Aiistotle  was  being  exploited  in  the 
interest  of  the  Church,  to  a  series  also  of  Aristotelian 
thinkers,  trained,  not  in  the  fathers,  but  in  the  Koran, 
and  who  appear  first  of  all  in  the  East,  and  afterwards  in 
Spain.  For  their  acquaintance  with  the  writings  of  the 
Stagirite,  the  Arabians  were  largely  indebted  to  the 
Nestorian  Christians  of  Syria.  The  physician  of  the 
Prophet  himself  was  a  Nestorian.  But  it  was  not  until 
the  reign  of  the  Abbassides,  in  the  eighth  century,  that 
the  medical  and  philosophical  Greek  literature  came 
generally  into  vogue  with  the  learned  Saracen.  The  first 
Arabian' translation  of  Aristotle  dates  from  the  beginning 
of  the  ninth  century. 

About  the  same  time,  or  rather  later,  flourished  Alkendi, 
to  whom  the  English  Eoger  Bacon  was  much  indebted. 
He  was  the  first  to  attempt  to  place  the  Islamite  theology 
on  a  rational  basis.  As  Professor  Wallace  observes 
(Encyclopsedia  Britannica,  9th  ed.,  art.  "  Arabian  Phi- 
losophy "),  "  there  were  schoolmen  amongst  the  believers 
in  the  Koran,  no  less  than  amongst  the  Latin  Chris- 
tians. At  the  very  moment  when  Mohammedanism  came 
into  contact  with  the  older  civilisations  of  Persia,  Baby- 
lonia, and  Syria,  the  intellectual  habits  of  the  new  converts 
created  difficulties  with  regard  to  its  very  basis,  and  proved 
tl^emselves  a  prolific  source  of  diversity  in  the  details 
of}  interpretation." 

taking  at  the  philosophical  problem  from  the  point  of 
vie\r'='lf  Mohammedan  monotheism,  the  difficulty  was  to 
reconcile  the  ascription  of  manifold  attributes  to  a  being 
whose  essence  was  unity.  The  next  in  interest  was  the 
relation  of  the  Divine  omnipotence  to  the  freedom  of  the 
human  will.  But  the  philosophical  genius  of  the  Semitic 
mind  was  not  sufficiently  great  to  deal  with  these  questions 


120  MEDIEVAL   PHILOSOPHY. 

satisfactorily  to  itself  without  the  assistance  of  European 
thought.  It  is  a  noteworthy  circumstance  that  the  phi- 
losophy of  Aristotle  appears  in  its  purest  form  in  the 
Middle  Ages,  in  the  works  of  the  Arabian  writers. 
Next  to  Alkendi  comes  the  so-called  Alfarabi,  who  died 
A.D.  050.  His  philosophy  was  buried  in  the  darkness 
of  a  secret  order,  such  was  the  suspicion  with  which  his 
rationalising  tendencies  were  regarded. 

One  of  the  most  important  of  the  philosophers  of  the 
East,  was  Avicenna  (born  980).  In  him  the  question  of 
Nominalism  and  Eealism  resolved  itself,  not  after  the 
manner  of  Abelard  in  the  West,  by  a  destructive  criticism 
of  the  rival  theories,  but  by  a  recognition  of  their  equal 
justification.  According  to  Avicenna,  all  universals  exist 
ante  res  in  the  Divine  understanding,  iyi  rebus,  as  the  real 
predicates  of  things,  and  post  res,  as  the  abstract  concepts 
formed  by  the  human  mind.  At  the  head  of  Avicenna's 
metaphysic  stands  the  absolutely  simple,  necessary,  and 
perfect  essence.  This  is  the  Good  towards  which  every- 
thing tends,  and  from  its  particiiDation  in  which  its  relative 
perfection  is  derived.  Notwithstanding  its  unity,  this 
principle  embraces  as  determinations  of  its  thought,  the 
necessary  (as  distinguished  from  the  merely  contingent)  in 
all  real  objects.  Opposed  to  this  abstract  principle  oiform, 
is  the  liyle  or  matter.  The  matter  of  Avicenna  is,  like  that  of 
Aristotle,  Plato,  and  their  successors,  merely  the  principle 
of  limitation,  of  non-being,  of  contingency,  in  which  the 
whole  sense-world  partakes  ;  in  other  words,  the  principle 
of  plurality  and  potentiality,  as  against  that  of  unity  and 
actuality.  Nature  is  the  synthesis  of  these  fundamental 
principles.  The  passage  from  the  higher  to  the  lower  is  to 
be  conceived  as  eternal.  The  cause  which  gives  reality  to 
things  is  equally  necessary  to  preserve  their  reality.  It  is 
an  error  to  suppose  that  once  brought  into  being,  objects 
would  remain  so  of  themselves.  Avicenna,  as  a  natural 
consequence  of  this  doctrine,  teaches  the  eternity  of  the 
world. 

It  is  unnecessary  to  enter  upon  the  manner  in  which 
Avicenna  brings  this  dualistic  system  into  conformity 
with  his  theological  creed.  Suffice  it  to  say,  that  any 
contradiction   between    the   doctrine  of   reason  and  the 


THE   ARABIANS   AND   JEWS.  121 

revelation  of  the  Prophet,  is  to  him  an  impossibility.  In 
practice  he  advocates  asceticism  as  a  means  of  freeing 
the  soul  from  the  bondage  of  matter,  and  raising  it  to 
the  intelligible  world,  which  is  its  proper  destination. 

Al  Ghazzali  (born  1059)  represents  the  sceptical  side  of 
Arabian  philosophy,  as  Avicenna  does  the  mystical. 
.His  work  may  be  described,  like  that  of  the  late  Dean 
Mansel's  '  Limits  of  Religious  Thought,'  and  Mr.  Balfour's 
*  Defence  of  Philosophic  Doubt,'  as  an  effort  to  resuscitate 
a  popular  theology  by  a  demonstration  that  pliilosophic 
conceptions  are  as  unreliable,  and  as  susceptible  to 
negative  criticism,  as  those  of  common  experience,  which 
philosophy  pretends  to  undermine.  The  consequence  of 
the  scepticism  of  Al  Ghazzali  was  the  triumph  throughout 
the  East  of  unphilosophical  Mohammelan  orthodoxy. 
Spain  became  henceforth  the  chief  theatre  of  Saracen 
learning. 

The  first  figure  that  strikes  us  in  the  Moorish  Empire  is 
Abu  Beker,  who  was  born  at  Saragossa,  towards  the  end 
of  the  eleventh  century.  He  wrote  only  small  treatises, 
most  of  which  are  lost.  The  most  famous  of  these,  '  The 
Guide  of  the  Lonely,'  treats  of  the  stages  through  which 
the  soul  rises  from  the  instinct  that  it  possesses  in  common 
with  the  lower  animals,  to  the  active  intellect,  which  is  an 
emanation  of  the  Deity  Himself.  This  is,  as  with  Avicenna, 
by  a  progressive  freeing  of  itself  from  the  potentiality  and 
multiplicity  of  sense.  Abu  Beker  is  chiefly  interesting  as 
leading  up  to  the  greatest  of  all  the  Mohammedan  thinkers, 
Averroes. 

Averroes  was  born  at  Cordova  in  the  year  1120,  and  died 
in  Morocco,  as  physician,  in  the  last  year  of  the  century. 
His  veneration  for  Aristotle  amounted  almost  to  adoration, 
his  works  chiefly  consisting  of  commentaries  on  the  master, 

Averroes  is  strong  in  his  polemic  against  the  doctrine 
of  creation  out  of  nothing,  and  in  his  rehabilitation  of  the 
Aristotelian  principle  of  evolution.  What  is  called  crea- 
tion is  nothing  but  the  transition  from  potentiality  to 
actuality.  Matter  (  ontains  within  it  all  forms,  according 
to  their  possibility ;  they  do  not  require  to  be  super- 
induced upon  it  from  without,  as  in  the  Platonic  doctrine 


122  MEDIiEVAL  PHILOSOPHY. 

of  Avicenna,  but  to  be  merely  evolved,  the  distinction 
betweeen  potentiality  or  possibility,  i.e.,  matter,  and  actuality, 
i.e.,  form,  existing  only  in  our  limited  thought,  The 
philosopher  should  recognise  this.  He  should  see  that  the 
oft-repeated  question  as  to  whether  chaos  or  matter  has 
preceded  or  followed  07'der  or  form,  from  bis  point  of  view, 
has  no  meaning,  since  the  merely  temporal  distinction  of 
possibility  and  actuality  is  for  him  merged  in  the  higher 
category  of  neceissity.  Averroes  found  in  his  religion  what 
he  was  expounding  in  a  rational  form,  shadowed  forth  in 
images  and  symbols.  Only  a  few  could  attain  the  highest 
goal,  viz.  philososophical  truth ;  for  the  rest,  the  popular 
creed  was  necessary.  With  Averroes  the  series  of  the 
Saracen  thinkers  closes.  Their  influence  is  readily  discover- 
able in  the  writings  of  Albertus  Magnus,  Thomas  Aquinas, 
and  indeed,  all  the  later  schoolmen. 

Before  proceeding  to  again  take  up  the  thread  of  Western 
speculation  proper,  we  must  cast  a  glance  at  the  con- 
temporary Jewish  philosophy,  a  type  of  which  we  may 
find  in  Maimonides.  This,  although  possessing  no  espe- 
cial bearing  on  what  immediately  follows,  will  have  its 
importance  when  we  come  to  treat  of  Spinoza. 

The  Jewish  philosophy  of  the  middle  ages  consists 
partly  in  the  Kabbala,  which  was  a  secret  doctrine, 
claiming  great  antiquity,  but  in  all  probability  not  dating 
from  earlier  than  the  middle  of  the  ninth  century;  and 
partly  in  a  Judaistic  Aristotolianism,  traceable  immediately 
to  the  Arabian  thinkers,  especially  Averroes.  The  doctrine 
of  the  Kabbala  is  comprised  in  two  books,  called  resj^ectively 
Jezirah,  or  Creation,  and  SoJiar,  or  Illumination.  It  is  the 
former  book  which  contains  the  original  Kabbalistic 
doctrine,  the  latter  being  avowedly  the  production  of  a 
Spanish  Jew  of  the  thirteenth  century.  It  will  suffice  to 
state  that  the  doctrines  contained  in  these  books  are  simply 
a  mixture  of  Neo-Platonic,  Neo- Pythagorean,  Parsic,  and 
other  theosophies. 

The  Moorish  Empire  was  the  happy  hunting-ground  of 
all  searchers  after  knowledge  and  si^eculative  freedom  in 
the  middle  ages.  In  spite  of  not  unfrequent  bursts  of 
intolerance,  thought  was  probably  freer  in  Spain  than  in 


THE   ARABIANS    AND   JEWS.  123 

any  other  European  country.  It  was  not  alone  Mussulman 
thinkers  and  scholars  that  found  a  home  there ;  Christians 
and  Jews  taught  and  studied  side  by  side  with  them. 
The  civilisation  which  produced  the  Alhambra  and  the 
Escorial  can  boast  not  only  Averroes,  but  Avicebron  and 
Maimonides. 

The  first  Jewish  philosopher  of  any  note  is  Avicebron, 
author  of  the  work  Fons  Vitse,  mu(;h  quoted  by  the 
schoolmen.  He  was  born  at  the  beginning  of  the  eleventh 
century,  at  Malaga,  and  died  aliout  1070.  His  main  thesis 
is  the  universality  of  the  opposition  of  Matter  and  Form 
(or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  of  Genus  and  Differentia), 
throughout  the  sensible,  no  less  than  the  intelligible  and 
moral  worlds ;  and  at  the  same  time,  their  indissoluble 
conjunction.  Will  alone  transcends  this  opposition,  and 
hence  cannot  be  defined,  but  only  seized  by  intuition. 
Avicebron  was  a  pronounced  Pantheist,  and  his  work  was 
in  consequence  shunned  by  the  orthodox,  no  less  among 
the  Jews  than  the  Christians. 

Moses  Ben  Maimon,  or  Maimonides,  who  was  a  native  of 
Cordova,  was  born  1135,  and  died,  1204,  at  Cairo.  He  was 
alike  among  his  co-religionists  and  the  outer  world  the 
most  highly  esteemed  of  all  the  mediseval  Hebrew  thinkers. 
Although  much  influenced  by  his  Mohammedan  con- 
temporaries and  predecessors  in  the  field  of  i:)hilosophical 
research,  having  studied  under  the  famous  Averroes,  he 
none  the  less  cultivated  with  assiduity  the  writings  of 
Aristotle  himself.  He  was  a  voluminous  writer,  not  only 
on  philosophy  but  also  on  law  and  medicine.  His  main 
doctrines  were  the  impossibility  of  predicating  any 
positive  attributes  of  the  Deity ;  with  this  was  con- 
nected his  division  of  all  existence  into  the  Makrokosmos 
and  Mikrokosmos,  terms  which  play  such  a  large  part 
among  the  alchemists  and  the  pseudo-physicists  of  a  later 
age.  Maimonides,  in  spite  of  his  devotion  to  Aristotle, 
refused  to  admit  the  eternity  of  the  world  a  parte  ante. 
The  divine  intelligence  is,  according  to  his  doctrine, 
connected  with  the  singular  or  individual  through  the 
human  intelligence.  In  itself  it  only  contains  the 
universal  forms  of  things. 

The  writings  of  Maimonides  soon  became  widely  circu- 


124  MEDIEVAL   PHILOSOPHY. 

lated,  and  were  much  commented  upon.  It  was  chiefly 
through  his  contemporary,  Gersonides,  that  they  were 
made  known  to  the  Gentile  world. 


THE  LATER  SCHOOLMEN. 

Albertus  Magnus., 

This  eminent  schoolman  and  reputed  magician  was 
born  in  Swabia,  about  the  year  1193,  receiving  his 
education  at  the  university  of  Padua.  In  his  thirty-sixth 
year  Albertus  repaired  to  Cologne,  as  professor  in  the 
Dominican  College  there.  He  is  also  said  to  have  taught 
in  several  other  places,  amongst  them  Strasbourg  and 
Paris,  but  subsequently  returned  to  Cologne  at  a  time 
when  Thomas  Aquinas  was  beginning  to  achieve  distinc- 
tion. After  much  wandering  in  France  and  German}^  he 
died  in  the  year  1280,  having  outlived  his  famous  pu2)il 
*'  the  angelic  doctor." 

Albertus  Magnus  was  the  first  of  the  schoolmen  to 
expound  the  Aristotelian  philosophy  in  systematic  order, 
at  the  same  time  taking  account  of  its  various  Arabian 
commentators,  and  to  seek  to  bring  the  whole  mass — 
original  form  and  later  developments  —  into  possible 
harmony  with  ecclesiastical  dogma.  He  expounds  his 
modified  version  of  "  the  philosopher "  in  a  series  of 
writings  which  form  a  running  commentary  on  the 
Aristotelian  text.  His  theory  of  the  Universal  is  nearly 
identical  with  that  of  Avicenna.  It  is  universale  ante  rem 
in  the  divine  mind  ;  universale  in  re  in  the  synthesis  of 
realit}'^ ;  and  universale  post  rem  as  the  mental  concept. 
Albertus  is  careful  to  separate  the  Trinitarian  doctrine  of 
the  Church  and  the  dogmas  connected  therewith  from  his 
rational  or  philosophic  theology.  He  none  the  less  rejects 
the  Aristotelian  doctrine  of  the  eternity  of  the  world, 
holding  fast  in  this  case  to  the  Church  dogma  of  a  creation 
in  time.  Albertus,  with  Aristotle  and  Plato,  contends  for 
the  materiality  of  the  soul  and  its  independence  of  the 
body  so  far  as  its  existence  is  concerned,  although  not  in 


THE   LATER   SCHOOLMEN.  125 

respect  of  it  as  an  active  agent  in  the  real  world.  The 
ethics  of  Albertns  rest  entirely  on  the  principle  of  the 
freedom  of  the  will.  His  attempt  to  combine  the 
Aristotelian  morality  with  the  Christian  is  more  ingenious 
than  successful. 

Thomas   Aquinas. 

Thomas  of  Aquino,  born  1225,  at  the  castle  of  his  father, 
a  Neapolitan  count,  is  the  central  figure  among  the  later 
schoolmen.  His  abilities  being  early  recognised,  he  was 
sent  to  the  Dominican  School  in  Cologne,  where  Albertus 
Magnus  was  then  lecturing.  He  followed  Albertus  to 
Paris,  and  back  again  to  Cologne,  there  assuming  the 
position  of  Magister  Studentium.  He  subsequently  gave 
courses  of  lectures  in  most  of  the  chief  universities  of 
Europe,  while  at  the  same  time  engaged  in  affairs  of  State, 
both  in  France  and  Italy,  and  active  in  all  the  public 
business  of  the  Church.     He  died  in  1274. 

Thomas  Aquinas  may  be  described  as  the  spirit  of 
Scholasticism  incarnate.  His  Smnma  Theologia  is  an 
attempt  to  realise  the  scholastic  ideal  of  an  all-embracing 
system  of  knowledge  comprehending  philosophy  proper, 
theology,  and  such  physical  speculations  of  an  alchemistio 
character,  which  then  did  duty  for  science. 

The  grand  principle  on  which  Aquinas  based  his 
system  was  that  there  were  two  sources  of  knowledge, — 

revelation, a,nd_rea&au. ThiLiiliiefldiaracterii^tic  of  i-evela- 

tion  is  the  mysterious  and  incomprehensible  guise  in 
which  its  truths  are  conveyed,  but  which  are  to  be 
belieye^^in  spite  of  this.  The  channels  of  revelation  are 
the  Hebrew  Scriptures  and  Church  tradition. 

The  Eeason  of  Aquinas  is  not  to  be  confounded  with 
the  individual  reason.  It  is  the  other  main  source  of 
knowledge,  its  artery  being  the  writings  of  the  Greeks, 
especially  of  Plato  and  Aristotle.  In  both  these  two 
channels  of  knowledge  there  is  a  higher  and  a  lower 
sphere,  the  latter  of  which,  alone,  man  can  hope  to  attain. 
Though  distinct  for  us,  in  the  last  resort.  Reason  and 
revelation  alike  draw  from  the  same  ultimate  source, 
namely,  God,  or  the  Absolute  One.  Thomas  Aquinas  did 
for  the   Christian   theology  what   Averroes   did  for   the 


126  MEDIEVAL   PHILOSOPHY, 

Moslem,  and  Maimonides  for  the  Jewish.  He  supplied  it 
with  a  fairly  coherent,  philosophical  dress.  In  his  theory 
of  the  universal,  Aquinas  follows  his  master,  Albertus 
Magnus,  who,  as  we  have  seen,  in  his  turn  follows 
Avicenna.  Eealism  (whether  Platonic  or  Aristotelian), 
and  Nominalism,  alike  have  their  relative  justification. 
In  the  agreement  of  things  with  the  eternal  ideas  consists 
tlieir  truth;  in  the  agreement  of  our  thoughts  with  the 
things,  consists  the  truth  for  us.  The  connection  between 
the  metaphysic  and  theology  of  Aquinas  is  seen  when  he 
comes  to  treat  oiForm  as  independent  Substance,  in  which 
way  the  existence  of  spiritual  being  is  explained.  The 
angels  of  Aquinas,  like  those  of  Philo,  are  simply 
personified  universals. 

In  treating  the  Scholastic  period  generally,  but  more 
especially  a  writer  like  Aquinas,  it  is  hard  to  say  where 
philosophy  ends  and  theology  begins,  for  in  spite  of 
St.  Thomas's  primary  distinction,  we  find  the  theological 
method  named  pervading  the  whole  current  of  his  thought, 
as  of  that  of  the  Schoolmen  generally. 

The  influence  of  the  "Angelic  Doctor,"  as  he  was 
termed,  on  the  thought,  and  more  than  all,  on  the 
terminology  of  subsequent  ages,  must  not  be  measured 
by  the  comparatively  limited  space  we  can  aiford,  or, 
indeed,  that  it  is  necessary,  to  devote  to  him,  in  a  work 
like  the  present.  "  Were  the  importance  of  a  school 
determined  by  the  number  of  its  adherents  and  its  long 
continuance,"  says  Erdmann,  "none  could  compare  with 
that  of  the  Albertists,  as  they  were  originally,  or  the 
Thomists,  as  they  were  afterwards  called.  There  are 
even  many  who  see  in  Thomas  at  the  present  dsij  the 
incarnation  of  the  philosophical  reason."  The  present 
pope  Leo  XIII.,  in  1879,  constituted  Thomas  Aquinas  the, 
so  to  speak,  official  exponent  of  the  philosophical  side  of 
Catholicism.  Not  long  after  his  death,  however,  he  had 
already  obtained  the  same  position  among  the  Dominican 
order  to  which  he  had  belonged.  There  can  b^s  no  doubt 
or  question,  whatever  may  be  our  opinion  of  the  value  of 
the  scholastic  philosophy  in  general,  or  of  that  of  St. 
Thomas  in  particular,  that  he  was  one  of  the  subtlest  and 
acutest  intellects  that  have  ever  lived.      The  s  ervices  he 


THE   LATER   SCHOOLMEN.  127 

has  rendered  in  giving  precision  to  philosophical  termin- 
ology mnst  alone,  apart  from  all  question  of  the  particular 
tenets  associated  with  his  name,  render  him  deserving  of 
the  gratitude  of  all  subsequent  thinkers. 

Duns  Scotus. 

John  Duns  Scotus,  the  precise  year  and  place  of  whose 
birth  are  somewhat  uncertain,  though  the  probabilities 
seem  in  favour  of  a  Scottish  origin,  flourished  during  the 
latter  half  of  the  thirteenth  century.  He  is  reported  to 
have  studied  at  Merton  College,  Oxford,  where  he  became 
remarkably  proficient  in  all  branches  of  learning,  especially 
mathematics.  In  1301  he  was  appointed  Professor  of 
Philosophy  at  Oxford,  and  attracted  great  attention,  a 
fact  expressed  in  the  legend  that  no  less  than  thirty 
thousand  students  attended  his  classes.  He  acquired  his 
title  of  "  Doctor  Subtilis,"  on  account  of  the  dialectical 
ingenuity  he  displayed  in  bis  defence  of  the  doctrine  of 
the  immaculate  conception,  a  dogma  which  was  main- 
tained by  the  Franciscans,  to  whom  Scotus  belonged, 
against  the  Dominicans.  He  died,  it  is  said,  in  the  thirty- 
fifth   year   of  his   age   at   Cologne,  in   November,  1308. 

Though  the  Scotists,  or  followers  of  Scotus,  continued, 
till  the  close  of  the  Scholastic  period,  the  rivals  of  the 
Thomists  in  the  learned  world,  it  must  not  be  supposed 
that  he  was  any  the  less  a  realist  in  philosophy  than 
Aquinas  himself;  indeed,  Scotus  nay  be  regarded  as 
rt-presenting  the  harder  and  more  uncompromising  form 
of  the  realist  doctrine.  He  als'^  indicates  a  reaction 
against  the  eclecticism  of  Aquinas  in  another  respect. 
Aquinas,  as  we  know,  gave  to  reason  an  amount  of 
authority  independent  of  dogma ;  Scotus.  on  the  other 
hand,  will  not  admit  of  any  other  channel  of  knowledge 
than  the  ecclesiastical  one.  In  accordance  with  this 
position,  he  rejects  the  ontological  arguments  offered  by 
Aquinas  in  favour  of  the  existence  of  the  Deity,  whose 
being  and  attributes  he  proclaims  altogether  outsiclo  the 
sphere  of  reason.  The  most  important  of  the  writiiigs  of 
Scotus  consisted  of  commentaries  on  Aristotle  and  Lom- 
bardus.     His  strength  consists  rather  in  negative  criticism 


128  MEDIEVAL   PHILOSOPHY. 

than  in  constructive  thought.  This  is  connected,  according 
as  we  view  it,  either  as  cause  or  consequence  of  his 
fundamental  position,  which  amounted  to  denying  for  the 
reason  any  sphere  of  use  other  than  that  of  undermining 
its  own  pretensions.  To  him  who  proclaimed  the  un- 
conditional acceptance  of  the  Church's  doctrines  in  their 
very  letter  as  the  primary  duty,  it  was  not  likely  that 
any  attempt  at  constructing  a  rational  theology  would 
find  much  favour.  Scotus  is  what  Occam  was  still  more, 
a  Christian  Al  Ghazzali. 

All  things,  according  to  Scotus,  are  constituted  of  Form 
and  Matter  combined.  The  principle  of  individuation  he 
finds  in  Form.  The  special  individual  determination  or 
the  Thisness  (Jisecceitas)  imposes  itself  as  Form  on  the 
Matter  which  is  constituied  of  generic  and  specific 
character.  The  essence  of  individuation  is  distinguish- 
able in  the  things  as  well  as  in  the  intellect,  although  it 
has  no  existence  separable  from  them,  i.e.  the  Universal 
is  not  merely  potentially  present  in  the  object,  but 
actually  so.  Scotus  is  particularlj^  strong  in  his  assertion 
of  the  freedom  of  the  will,  which  he  declares  capable  of 
self-determination  without  motive.  It  will  be  sufficiently 
clear  from  this  brief  sketch  that  by  his  doctrine  of  the 
Thisness  (JisBcceitas),  or  principle  of  individuation,  not 
implying  any  limitation  or  deterioration  of  the  What- 
ness,  or  quiddity,  but  rather  the  completion  and  perfecting 
of  it,  Scotus  has  discarded  the  last  remnant  of  the  older 
Platonic  realism,  according  to  which  the  sense  element,  or 
in  other  words,  this  same  principle  of  individuation  was 
the  purely  negative  matter,  limiting  the  perfection  of  the 
universal  form,  which  inhered  in  it. 


William  of  Occam. 

William,  born  at  Occam  (now  Ockham),  in  Surrey,  a 
Franciscan  and  pupil  of  Duns  Scotus,  was  for  some  time 
professor  in  Paris.  Opposed  to  the  temporal  power  of  the 
Hierarchy,  in  accordance  with  the  principles  of  his  order, 
he  threw  himself  with  ardour  into  the  conflict  between 
the  French  Monarchy  and  the  Papacy  on  the  side  of  the 


THE   LATER   SCHOOLMEN.  129 

former.  Persecuted  by  the  papal  party,  he  fled  to  Padua, 
and  subsequently  to  Munich,  where  he  placed  himself 
under  the  protection  of  Ludwig  of  Bavaria.  He  died  in 
Munich  about  the  year  1347. 

In  William  of  Occam,  the  swan  of  scholasticism  sang  its 
death-song.  For  from  Occam's  new  arguments  and  re- 
statement of  the  position  of  Nominalism,  which  he 
championed,  resulted  the  bankruptcy  of  the  school- 
ardently  philosoj^hy.  Occam  was  as  much  opposed  to 
Scotism,  the  dominant  philosophy  of  his  order,  as  he 
was  to  the  Thomism  of  the  Dominicans.  His  definition 
of  a  Universal  is  interesting.  "  A  Universal  is,"  he 
says,  "  a  particular  intention  of  the  mind,  itself  capable 
of  being  predicated  of  many  things,  not  for  what  it  pro- 
perly is  itself,  but  for  what  those  things  are ;  so  that 
in  so  far  as  it  has  this  capacity  it  is  called  Universal,  but 
in  so  far  as  it  is  one  form  really  existing  in  the  mind,  it 
is  called  singular." 

With  Occam  the  great  controversy  respecting  Univer- 
sals  became  consciously  narrowed  to  a  purely  psycho- 
logical issue.  The  coincidence  between  much  in  his 
writings  with  the  doctrines  of  the  later  English  Em- 
piricist school  is,  allowing  for  scholastic  terminology 
striking.  According  to  Occam,  the  Species  {intelligibiles) 
of  the  Scotists  are  superfluous  entities.  It  is  rather 
the  actus  intelUgendi  itself  which  is  the  sign  of  the  thing. 
By  sign,  William  understands  that  by  which  one  thing 
is  distinguished  from  another  thing.  He  draws  a  line 
between  natural  signs,  or  signs  of  objects  over  which 
our  v/ill  has  no  control,  and  those  general  terms  forme p 
in  the  mind  which  can  be  called  up  and  dismissed 
at  pleasure.  The  former  constitute  our  percej)tions  or 
thoughts  of  things,  the  latter  are  merely  states  or  modi- 
fications of  the  soul  caused  by  these  perceptions.  But  it 
would  be  just  as  irrational  to  suppose  that  even  the  first 
of  these,  i.e.  our  necessary  thoughts,  or  our  perceptions 
through  sense,  resemble  the  things  perceived,  as  to 
suppose  that  the  sigh  resembles  the  pain  which  causes  it, 
or  the  smoke  the  fire.  Here  we  have  a  plain  statement, 
albeit  couched  in  scholastic  phraseology,  of  the  ordinaiy 
empirical  doctrine  of  a  world  of  "  things-in-themselves," 

K 


130  MEDIEVAL   PHILOSOPHY. 

which  are  the  cause  of  our  perceptions  but  concerning 
which  we  know  nothing  more.  The  second  order  of  signs, 
our  ideas  or  general  concepts,  have,  according  to  Occam, 
no  connection  whatever  with  things,  but  are  merely  built 
up  of  our  perceptions  of  things  and  serve  to  indicate 
these.  They  are  mere  words  or  names,  having  no  more 
resemblance  to  the  perceptions  which  gave  rise  to  them 
than  the  latter  in  their  turn  have  to  the  things  by 
which  they  are  caused. 

The  principle  of  Occam's  philosophical  method  is  well 
expressed  in  his  favourite  maxim  :  entia  non  sunt  multqjli- 
canda  p'seter  necessitatem.  Sufficiunt  singularia,  et  ita  tales 
res  universales  omnino  frustra  jpommtur.  He  makes  short 
work  of  distinctions  which,  until  then,  had  passed  as  the 
common  property  of  the  learned.  The  same  tendency  to 
simplification  is  observable  in  his  theology.  Like  his 
master  Duns,  he  denies  the  possibility  of  basing  theology 
on  reason. 

With  William  of  Occam,  the  philosophy  of  the  Church 
virtually  closes.  After  him  there  is  no  original  figure. 
The  various  schools  continued  to  furnish  writings  and 
disputations  up  to  the  period  of  the  Renaissance,  and  even 
later,  but  there  is  little  to  record  concerning  them. 

Among  the  best  works  giving  a  general  view  of  the  philosophy 
of  the  Middle  Ages  may  be  mentioned  Haureau,  de  la  philosopMe 
scolastique  (2  Yoll.  Par.  1850) ;  Kaulich,  Geschichte  der  sclwlastischen 
Philosophie  (Prague,  1863) ;  Stocld,  Geschichte  der  Fhilowphie  dea 
Mittelalters  (Mainz,  1862-66);  Frantl,  Gesch.  der  Logic  im  Ahend- 
Jande.  Muurice,  Medipeval  ^Philosophy,  in  Vol.  I.  of  his  Moral  and 
Metapliysical  Philosophy,  which  contains  perhaps  the  best  and  fullest 
English  monograph  on  the  subject.  For  the  Arabians  and  Jews 
may  be  consulted  Munk,  Melanges  de  philosophie  juive  et  arabe  (Paris, 
1859);  Ernest  Eenan,  Averroes  et  Vaverroisme  (Paris,  1852  ;  2nd  Ed. 
1865);  Geiger,  Moses  hen  Maimon  (Breslau,  1850);  a\so  Beer,  Philo- 
sophie und  philosophische  Schriftsteller  der  Juden  (Leipsic,  1852). 

About  the  time  that  Scholasticism  was  declining,  a  curious 
niovementsprHng  up  in  Germany.  This  was  the  so-called 
"  German  Mysticism "  of  the  fourteenth  and  fifteenth 
centuries.  It  is  in  the  main  concomitant  with  the  rise  of 
that  German  national  literature  which  was  brought  to  an 
untimety  end  by  the  Tliirty  Years'  War.  This  mystical 
movement  may  be  said  to  have  originated  with  the  Master 


THE   LATER   SCHOOLMEN.  131 

Ecliliart,  who,  tired  of  the  teachings  of  the  schools,  broke 
away  from  them  in  a  direction  which  led  directly  to  Jacob 
Bohme,  and  indirectly  to  the  Lutheran  Keformation. 
Johannes  Tauler,  of  Strasbourg,  may  be  also  mentioned  as 
one  of.the  leaders  of  this  movement.  Though  he  did  not 
add  much  in  substance  to  the  speculations  of  Eckhart,  he 
was  possessed  of  a  literary  style  which  his  predecessors 
lacked,  and  thus  contributed  to  popularise  them. 

The  most  important  work  of  this  school  in  its  influence 
on  German  thought  was  one  by  an  unknown  author,  sub- 
sequently published  by  Luther  as  "  A  German  Theology  '* 
{Eyn  deutsch  Tlieologia).  The  burden  of  the  whole  school 
is  the  evil  and  unreality  of  the  phenomenal  world ;  true 
reality  only  being  recognised  in  a  world  outside  the  limits 
of  time  and  space  to  which  man  must  attain  ere  he  rises  to 
his  higher  life.  We  have  in  them  an  apt  illustration  of 
history  repeating  itself.  To  Eckhart  and  his  followers,  as 
to  Plotinus,  the  goal  of  the  reason  is  found  in  the  absolute 
all-embracing  Unity  wherein  all  difference  is  abolished, 
Indeed  this  German  Mysticism  of  the  later  Middle  Ages 
is  little  but  a  reproduction  of  Neo-Platonic  theories,  con- 
siderable as  was  it8  practical  influence  and  results. 

On  the  German  Mystics  the  best  work  is  Praegers  Geschichte  der 
deutschen  Mystik  i-m  MittelaUer  (1st  Part,  Leipsic,  1875) ;  Rosenhrantz, 
Der  Deutsche  Mystik,  Konigsberg,  1836).  In  French,  Albert  Barran, 
Etudes  sur  qitelqties  tendences  du  mysticisme  avant  la  reformcitian 
(Strasbourg,  1868). 


K  2 


(    132    ) 


TRANSITION  TO  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY. 

THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  THE  KENAISSANCE. 

Feudalism  was  in  ruins.  Industry  and  Commerce  were 
rising  into  power.  Catholicism  was  rapidly  disintegrating 
as  a  system  even  in  spiritual  matters,  while  as  a  con- 
trolling factor  in  the  affairs  of  the  world  it  was  merely 
one,  by  no  means  the  greatest,  among  several  contending 
forces.  The  philosophy  of  the  schools  was  everywhere  in 
disrepute  among  earnest  and  independent  thinkers.  The 
art  of  printing  had  just  been  invented,  and  was  of  itself 
revolutionising  older  habits  of  thought.  The  New  World 
was  being  opened  up  by  enterprising  Spanish  and  Portu- 
guese mariners.  And  last,  but  not  least,  Constantinople 
had  but  recently  fallen  before  the  crescents  and  horsetails 
of  Mahomet  II.,  and  its  treasures,  literary  and  artistic, 
been,  in  consequence,  dispersed  throughout  the  Western 
World.  Such  was  Europe  as  the  fifteenth  century  closed, 
and  the  sixteenth  opened.  Among  a  crowd  of  diverse,  yet 
connected  factors,  each  contributing  its  quota  to  the  for- 
mation of  the  mental  character  of  an  epoch,  it  is  difficult 
to  assign  the  relative  importance  of  any  one  in  particular. 
Yet  it  is  sufficiently  obvious  that  it  was  the  last  event 
mentioned  which  gave  its  immediate  colouring  to  the 
philosophy  of  the  period. 

Little  as  the  so-called  Renaissance  has  in  common  with 
the  Middle  Ages  pure  and  simple,  it  yet  possesses  a 
distinct  mediasval  character  of  its  own,  just  as  the  period 
of  the  Christian  Roman  Empire  has  the  stamp  of  the 
civilization  of  antiquity  upon  it,  notwithstanding  the 
gnlf  which  divides  it  from  the  ancient  world  properly  so 
called.  The  industrial  middle  class  of  the  fifteenth 
century  were  so  far  nearer  allied  to  the  yeomen  and  free 
tenants  of  feudalism  than  to  the  commercial  classes  of 
modern  times.    In  the  same  way  the  hatred  of  scholasticism 


FICINUS   AND   PICUS.  133 

and  the  desire  to  start  afresh  on  the  lines  of  ancient 
thought  in  its  purity  did  not  prevent  the  philosophical 
literature  of  the  period  from  having  a  distinct  mediaeval 
and  scholastic  flavour. 

Early  in  the  fifteenth  century,  there  was  a  society  esta- 
blished in  Florence  by  a  Greek  named  Plethon,  the  com- 
mentator of  Plato,  under  the  special  j^rotection  of  Cosmo  de 
Medici,  for  the  study  of  the  works  of  Plato  untrammelled 
by  theological  scruples.  Marsilius  Ficinus  (1433-1499), 
who  taught  in  the  school,  was 'the  author,  in  addition  to  a 
work  entitled  Theologica  Platonica,  of  a  well-known 
Latin  translation  of  Plato.  Another  prominent  reviver  of 
Platonism  was  John  Picus  of  Mirandola.  Turning  from 
Platonism  to  Cabbalistic  mysticism  and  charlatanry,  Picus 
of  Mirandola  repaired  to  Kome  to  propound  nine  hundred 
theses  on  every  conceivable  subject,  logical,  ethical, 
mathematical,  metaphysical,  theological,  magical,  which 
he  offered  to  defend  against  all  comers.  By  these  he  suc- 
ceeded in  achieving  great  notoriety  at  the  time,  though 
not  without  falling  under  the  suspicion  of  heresy.  Picus 
died  at  the  early  age  of  thirty-one,  in  the  year  1494. 

Ficinus  and  Picus  may  be  taken  more  or  less  as  types 
of  the  average  philosophical  product  of  the  Eenaissance  in 
Italy.  Scholars  like  them  crowded  the  court  of  the  Medicis. 
The  great  speculative  result  of  the  classical  revival  of  the 
fifteenth  and  sixteenth  centuries  may  be  seen  in  the  Pagan- 
ism which  became  fashionable  among  the  upper  classes, 
extending  even  to  the  Papal  chair  itself.  A  state  of 
things  prevailed  similar  in  many  respects  to  that  presented 
by  the  French  pre-revolutionary  salons  of  the  eighteenth 
century,  of  which  it  was  indeed  the  precursor.  The 
dominant  classes,  while  amid  their  own  circle  avowedly 
an ti- Christian,  were  publicly,  and  before  the  common 
people,  devout  members  of  the  Church. 

The  cultured  indifferentism  of  Italy  was  in  striking 
contrast  with  the  earnestness  felt  and  displayed  in  religious 
matters  the  other  side  of  the  Alps.  To  Leo  X.  the  sale  of 
indulgences  seemed  a  short  and  easy  method  of  raising 
money,  as  little  objectionable  as  any.  This  opinion 
was  doubtless  shared  by  the  higher  clergy,  and  all 
those  who,  whether  Italian  or  not,  had  come  directly  under 


134         THE   PHILOSOPHY   OF   THE   RENAISSANCE. 

the  influence  of  the  Eenaissance.  Populus  vult  decipi  et 
decijnatur  was  their  motto;  and  it  was  surely  only  fair 
that  the  populus  should  pay  for  its  deception.  To  Luther 
and  his  confreres  of  the  German  Reformation,  whose  contact 
with  the  Eenaissance  was  only  indirect  and  second-hand, 
and  who  possessed  in  addition,  the  fierce  earnestness  of  the 
northern  temperament,  the  whole  body  of  Christian  dogma 
was  of  serious  and  vital  moment.  To  the  man  who 
believed  himself  to  be  continually  wrestling  with  the 
devil,  it  is  obvious  the  said  of  free  leave  of  sinning  was 
horrible  in  the  extreme.  The  great  religious  conflict  of 
the  period  known  as  the  Reformation,  was  not  so  much 
the  struggle  of  a  new  religious  idea  with  the  old  Catholic 
one,  as  with  the  class-culture  of  the  Renaissance.  It  may 
be  roughly  characterised  as  a  conflict  between  the  two  great 
natural  groups  of  western  Europe — the  Latin  and  the 
Teutonic.  The  former  would  have  had  two  creeds,  that  of 
a  Paganised  culture  for  the  upper  classes  existing  con- 
currently with  abject  superstition  in  those  below  them  in 
the  social  scale ;  the  latter  contended  for  the  right  of  the 
growing  middle  classes  to  independent  judgment  within 
certain  limits  ;  i.e.  what  they  deemed  the  fundamental  arti- 
cles of  Christian  belief.  To  them  the  free-thought  and  eccle- 
siastical superstition  of  the  Latins  were  alike  abominable. 
But  it  was  an  indispensable  condition,  even  in  Italy 
itself,  great  as  was  the  latitude  allowed  in  speculation, 
that  none  should  endanger  the  authority  of  the  Church. 
Giordano  Bruno,  born  1548,  near  Naples,  originally  a 
Dominican,  found  this  to  his  cost.  In  consequence  of  his 
having  come  to  disbelieve  the  ecclesiastical  dogma,  he  left 
his  order,  a  fact  which  in  itself  must  have  constituted  him 
a  fool,  and  a  somewhat  dangerous  one  to  boot,  in  the  eyes 
of  his  brother  Italian  churchmen  of  the  period.  To  this 
noble-minded  man  the  lip-service  and  speculative  chicanery 
of  other  clerical  scholars  was  abhorrent.  He,  at  least, 
could  not  continue  professing  a  creed,  or  serving  a  church, 
in  whose  pretensions  he  disbelieved.  He  was  hence  com- 
pelled to  leave  Italy.  At  first  he  repaired  to  Geneva,  then 
the  capital  of  the  Reformation ;  but  the  "  reformed " 
doctrines,  so-called,  were  to  his  logical  mind  even  less 
satisfactory  than  the  Catholic  orthodoxy  he  had  forsaken. 


GIORDANO   BRUNO.  135 

From  tlience  he  went  to  Lyons,  Toulouse,  Paris,  and 
ultimately  to  Oxford  and  London.  He  found  a  temporary 
resting;- place  at  the  Court  of  Queen  Elizabeth,  and  hold 
disputations  at  Oxford,  It  has  even  been  conjectured, 
though  on  perhaps  insufficient  grounds,  that  while  in 
Londoh,  Bruno  made  the  acquaintance  of  Shakespeare, 
and  that  certain  philosophical  allusions  occurring  in 
"Hamlet"  ma}'-  be  traced  to  the  influence  of  his  conversa- 
tion on  the  poet.  But  the  spirit  of  wandering  again  seized 
Bruno ;  he  travelled  to  Wittenberg,  thence  to  Prague, 
subsequently  visiting  Frankfort-on-the-Maine,  where  he 
remained  some  little  time,  and  from  which  place  an  evil 
fate  seems  to  have  drawn  him  once  more  across  the  Alps 
into  his  native  country.  He  fell  into  the  hands  of  the 
Inquisition  soon  after  his  arrival,  and  was  conveyed  to 
Eonie  in  1593.  There  he  suffered  an  imprisonment  of 
some  years'  duration,  during  which  time  every  attemj^t, 
whether  by  force  or  cajolery,  to  induce  him  to  recant  his 
views  was  nobly  and  successfully  resisted.  When,  at  the 
beginning  of  1600,  he  was  sentenced  to  death,  Bruno  is 
reported  to  have  said  in  the  presence  of  the  Court,  "  It 
behoves  you  to  have  greater  fear  in  pronouncing  this 
sentence  than  I  have  in  receiving  it."  He  was  burnt  at 
Eome  on  the  17th  of  February,  1600.  A  statue  has  been 
erected  to  his  memory  at  Naples,  before  which  the  students, 
on  one  occasion,  burnt  an  encyclical  letter  of  Pope  Pius  IX. 

Bruno  is  certainly  by  far  the  most  important  and  original 
philosophic  figure  to  which  the  Renaissance  gave  birth. 
An  ardent  disciple  of  the  new  physical  doctrines  of 
Copernicus,  he  was  not  satisfied  with  philosojihising  en 
the  old  Platonic  or  Aristotelian  lines,  but  sought  a  theory 
of  the  universe  which  should  embrace  the  new  science. 
Bruno's  admiration  for  the  older  Greek  philosophers 
was  great ;  he  placed  them  before  either  Plato  or 
Aristotle,  for  the  latter  of  whom  he  seems  to  have  had  a 
genuine  hatred.  An^ixagoras,  Herakleitos,  Pythagoris,  he 
held  in  high  esteem;  but  the  thinker  wlio  most  immedately 
influenced  him  was  perhaps  Nicolas  of  Chusa,  the  celebrated 
German  ecclesiastic  and  mystic  of  the  fifteenth  century. 

To  Bruno  God  was  simply  the  immanent  princix:)le  of 
the  universe,  or  world-soul.    Bruno  attacks  what  he  con- 


136         THE   PHILOSOPHY   OF   THE   EENAISSANCE. 

ceives  the  dualism  of  Matter  and  Form;  the  Form  is 
immanent  in  all  Matter  of  which  it  is  only  an  aspect.  Like 
his  enemies,  the  Scholastics  and  the  Arabian  Aristotelians, 
he  held  to  the  three-fold  existence  of  ideas,  or  universals, 
ante  res,  in  rebus,  and  post  res — metaphj^sically  in  the 
ultimate  unity  or  world-soul,  physically  in  the  real 
world,  and  logically  in  tlie  sign,  symbol  or  notion.  God, 
or  the  universal  substance  of  all  things,  is  related  to  the 
real  world  as  the  universal  to  the  particular.  In  the 
laws  of  nature,  which  are  the  expression  of  his  being, 
Bruno  discovers  true  freedom.  But  the  determining 
and  infinitely  actual  principle  presupposes  a  possible 
principle,  which  becomes  determined.  The  other  pole 
of  the  philosophic  equation  is  therefore  the  old  prin- 
ciple of  Matter,  or  the  infinitely  possible.  Thus,  as 
might  be  expected  from  the  nature  of  things,  Bruno  was 
bound,  when  once  he  attacked  the  ultimate  philosophical 
problem,  to  express  himself  in  that  same  Aristotelian  fashion 
which  he  elsewhere  condemns  as  dualistic.  The  position 
held  by  Bruno  in  reference  to  the  problem  of  Monism  or 
Pluralism  is  not  quite  clear.  His  work  De  Monade  Numero 
et  Figura,  seems  to  incline  to  the  latter;  the  De  Immenso 
et  Innumerahilibus  to  the  former  ;  but  possibly  he  had  never 
clearly  propounded  the  question  to  himself.  God,  or  the 
universal  principle,  inasmuch  as  it  embraces  the  sum  of 
things,  is  the  maximum  possibile  ;  inasmuch  as  it  is  equally 
present  in  every  atom,  the  minimum  possibile.  It  compre- 
hends in  itself  every  other  contradiction  ;  thus,  that  which 
is  everywhere  centre,  is  at  once  everywhere  and  nowhere 
periphery,  &c.  The  one  principle  is  the  same,  not  only  in 
kind,  but  in  degree,  whether  in  the  plant,  the  animal,  or 
the  stone.  The  infinite  possibilities  of  the  one  substance  are 
realised  successively  in  the  order  of  time,  which  is  also  in- 
finite. As  Erdmann  remarks,  if  on  the  one  side  Bruno  may 
be  regarded  as  a  forerunner  of  Spinoza,  on  the  other  he  is 
none  the  less  a  forerunner  of  Leibnitz.  The  monad  is 
the  principle  of  the  working  of  the  soul.  Every  order  of 
beings  is  perfect  according  to  its  kind  ;  there  is  no  absolute, 
but  only  a  relative  evil.  These  principles  are  developed 
on  Pythagorean  lines. 

Bruno  is  remarkable  for  having  been  the  first  to  attempt 


REUCHLIN,   ETO.  137 

the  incorporation  of  the  new  scientific  conceptions  into 
a  philosophical  system.  He  is  moreover  interesting 
from  his  having  been  the  first  thinker  in  the  modern 
world  who  openly  and  definitely  broke  with  Christi- 
anity. A  true  son  of  the  Kenaissance,  in  spite  of 
his  originality,  his  philosophy,  like  his  character,  was 
essentially  formed  on  a  Pagan  mould,  and  he  knew  it. 
But  unlike  the  rank  and  file  of  the  scholars  and  gram- 
marians of  the  age,  he  boldly  attacked  the  dogmas  which 
he  disbelieved,  and  which  were  abhorrent  to  him,  and 
attacked  them  too  in  no  compromising  or  half-hearted 
manner. 

In  this  he  was  not  followed  by  his  countryman  and 
contemporary  Thomas  Campanella,  also  a  man  of  con- 
siderable original  power,  though  inferior  to  Bruno.  Cam- 
panella is  chiefly  noteworthy  as  the  immediate  prede- 
cessor of  Descartes,  in  making  the  certainty  of  the  actual 
moment  of  consciousness  the  starting-point  of  his  phi- 
losophy ;  and  also  in  having  employed  the  ontological 
argument  to  prove  the  existence  of  the  Deity.  In  many 
respects  he  approached  Bruno,  even  in  the  latter's  Pan- 
theism, but  he  nevertheless  always  contrived  to  keep  on 
good  terms  with  the  Church,  being  in  his  later  years 
a  strong  advocate  of  Papal  domination. 


THE   SIXTEENTH-CENTUEY   ALCHEMISTS   AND 
COSMIC  SPECULATORS. 

The  sixteenth  century  was  eminently  an  age  of  travelling 
scholars.  The  whole  of  civilized  Europe  was  at  this  period 
of  universally  awakening  intellectual  activity,  literally 
overrun  with  students  who  contrived  to  support  themselves 
chiefly  by  obtaining  hospitality  in  return  for  some  slight 
service,  educational,  medical,  or  divinatory;  among  these 
were  brilliant  disputationists  and  scholars  like  Giordano 
Bruno  and  Johannes  Eeuchlin,  &c.,  but  the  vast  number 
obtained  a  meagre  subsistence  by  soothsaying,  fortune- 
casting  and  healing  (or  the  reverse).  It  was  an  age  of  rest- 
less intellectual  cravings  and  of  ceaseless  wandering.    The 


138  ALCHEMISTS   AND   COSMIC   SPECULATOES. 

Faust  legend — the  last  instance  in  history  of  the  complete 
envelopment  of  a  personality  in  myth — is  a  perfect  embodi- 
ment of  the  spirit  of  the  sixteenth  century.  .  It  was  em- 
phatically the  epoch  of  the  occult  sciences,  so-called.  The 
strange  lore  which  had  lain  buried  in  monasteries,  shunned 
by  all  but  a  few  doctors  during  the  Middle  Ages,  was  now 
the  common  property  of  every  man  possessed  of  a  little  , 
learning.  Add  to  this,  that  the  new  culture  of  Greek  and 
Hebrew  had  opened  up  sources  hitherto  sealed.  As  Italy 
may  be  taken  as  the  tj^pical  country  for  the  more  purely 
literary  and  artistic  side  of  the  Eenaissance,  so  Germany 
(understanding  by  the  term  the  German-speaking  countries 
of  Central  Europe)  may  be  regarded  as  the  typical  country 
of  this  magical-theosophic  aspect  of  it,  though,  of  course, 
in  neither  case  is  any  exclusiveness  implied.  The  inter- 
mingling of  theosophic  lore  with  the  rising  physical 
science  was  most  systematically  carried  out  in  Germany. 
Most  of  the  theosophic  and  alchemistic  notions  which  now 
became  popular,  the  elixir  vitas,  the  philosojDher's  stone, 
the  elemental  spirits,  are  immediately  traceable  to  the 
Kabbala  (see  above,  p.  121),  the  authors  of  which  probably 
drew  from  Coptic,  Persian  and  other  Oriental  sources,  in 
addition  to  the  Talmud  and  other  Rabbinical  writings.* 

The  first  to  introduce  the  study  of  Hebrew,  and  especially 
of  the  Kabbala,  into  Germany  was  Johannes  Reuchlin,  who 
studied  under  Picus  of  Mirandola  and  Ficinus  in  Italy, 
and  subsequently  settled  at  Tubingen.  The  story  of  his 
successful  conflict  on  behalf  of  Hebrew  literature  with  the 
monks  of  Cologne,  in  which  he  was  supported  by  the  re- 
formers Melancthon  and  Ulrich  von  Hutten,  is  well  known. 
He  wrote  a  treatise  De  arte  cabhalistica.  After  Eeuchlin 
maybe  mentioned  Cornelius  Agrippa  von  Nettesheim  (1486- 
1530),  who  wrote  a  treatise  De  occulta pJiilosophia.  Agrippa  ^ 
was  a  true  son  of  his  century,  spending  his  life  in  courts, 
universities,  on  the  battle-field,  and  anon  in  studious  re- 
tirement, seldom  remaining  more  than  two  or  three  years 

*  The  Rosicrucians,  the  Freemasons,  the  Illuminati  of  the  eighteenth, 
century,  all  date  indirectly  from  this  Alchemistic  or  rather  physico-' 
theosophic  movement  of  the  sixteenth  century.  The  attempt  to  con- 
nect Freemasonry  with  the  mediaeval  craft-guild  of  masons  can  only 
pass  muster  with  those  who  have  not  studied  the  period  in  question. 


PARACELSUS.  '  139 

at  the  utmost  in  the  same  place.  Like  Giordano  Bruno, 
these  writers,  especially  Agrippa,  drew  much  from  the 
writings  of  the  mystic  Nicolas  of  Chusa,  whose  mathe- 
matical speculations  furnished  material  for  many  of  the 
magical  formula3  of  the  time. 

Jjut  the  man  in  whom  the  whole  intellectual  and  moral 
temper  of  the  century  was  most  perfectly  embodied  is 
in  the  erratic  person  who  rejoiced  in  the  name  of 
PJiilippus  Aureolus  Theophrastus  Bomhastes  von  HoJienheim, 
though  better  known  by  his  surname  of  Paracelsus  (1493- 
1541).  He  is  a  true  prototype  of  the  Goethean  Faust. 
The  contempt  for  traditional  and  academic  teaching  and 
teachers,  the  universal  scepticism  culminating  in  the 
attempt  to  wring  from  nature  her  secrets  by  magic ; 

"  Ob  mich  durch  Geistes  Kraft  und  Mund 
Nicht  manch  Geheimaiss  wiirde  kund ; " 

the  ceaseless  wandering,  the  alternations  of  drunkenness 
and  debauchery  with  real  attempts  to  pluck  out  the  heart 
of  the  mystery  of  nature,  make  the  parallel  complete. 
Some  apology  may  be  deemed  necessary  for  introducing 
the  physical  speculators,  of  whom  we  take  Paracelsus  as 
the  type,  into  a  manual  of  the  history  of  philosophy. 
From  a  narrow  interpretation  of  the  word  philosophy  it 
might  perhaps  be  out  of  place,  but  the  interest  attaching 
to  the  first  dawnings  of  physical  science,  and  the  quaint 
blending  of  theosophy  and  physics,  which  coloured  more  or 
less  the  whole  thought  of  this  epoch  will,  we  fancy,  render 
any  formal  apology  unnecessary  to  those  who  take  a  broad 
view  of  the  evolution  of  speculative  thought. 

Paracelsus  spent  most  of  his  youth  in  the  manner  we 
have  described  as  common  at  the  time,  that  is,  wandering 
from  city  to  city  and  country  to  country,  practising 
astrology,  palmistry  and  magic  and  alchemy  generally. 
He  is  said  to  have  been  initiated  in  these  pseudo-sciences 
by  sundry  ecclesiastics.  In  the  course  of  his  travels 
he  visited  nearly  all  the  most  prominent  universities 
of  Europe.  Owing  to  the  reputation  gained  by  some 
cures  effected  on  important  personages,  he  obtained, 
in  1526,  the  professorship  of  medicine  in  the  Uniyer- 
sity  of  Basel.     His  first  act  on  assuming  the  chair  was 


140  ALCHEMISTS  AND   COSMIC   SPECULATOES. 

to  publicly  burn  the  treatises  of  Aristotle  and  Galen, 
for  whom  be  bad  a  special  antipathy.  His  discourses 
appear  to  have  been  delivered  in  a  manner  which,  whether 
Paracelsus  originated  it  or  not,  has  ever  since  been  asso- 
ciated with  his  name,  the  word  bombastic  dating  from  the 
medical  lectures  of  Bombastus  Paracelsus  at  Basel. 
Drunkenness  compelled  him  to  resign  his  chair,  and  again 
take  to  the  life  of  wandering  medicus,  divinator  and 
astrologer.  He  died,  like  his  friend  Cornelius  Agrippa, 
in  great  poverty,  at  Salzburg,  in  1541. 

Paracelsus  was  believed  by  his  contemporaries  to  have 
unveiled  the  secret  arcana  of  nature,  to  have  become 
possessed  not  only  of  the  power  of  transmuting  metals, 
but  of  the  philosopher's  stone,  the  elixir  of  life,  and 
many  other  things.  He  is  usually  decried  as  a  mere 
charlatan  by  historians,  but  probably  with  insufficient 
cause.  There  is  little  reason  for  doubting  that  Paracelsus 
believed  in  the  main  in  the  principles  he  was  propounding, 
and  at  least  in  the  general  possibility  of  obtaining  the 
powers  he  claimed  for  himself.  Living  in  a  magical  age, 
the  whole  of  Nature  presented  itself  naturally  enough  to 
his  mind  as  a  system  of  "  occult "  properties,  affinities 
and  agents.  Those  who  stigmatise  Paracelsus  as  a  con- 
scious impostor  must  surely  forget  the  state  of  science  at 
the  time,  and  the  universality  among  the  learned  of  the 
belief  in  astrology  and  alchemy.  These  beliefs  were  re- 
duced to  systematic  form  by  Paracelsus.  The  idea  traceable 
throughout  the  period  is  that  theosophy  supplies  a  key  not 
only  to  the  theoretical  interpretation  of  Nature,  but  to  the 
practical  application  of  its  laws  in  medicine,  &c.  Still,  on 
the  confines  of  the  Middle  Ages,  when  everything,  from  the 
highest  relations  of  Church  and  State  to  those  of  the  trade 
or  handicraft,  had  a  mystic  religious  significance,  it  was 
but  natural  the  new  phj^sical  science  should  be  conceived 
in  this  spirit.  A  scientific  method  did  not  exist,  and  men 
had  not  as  yet  become  accustomed  to  the  habit  of  special- 
isation, which  characterises  our  thought  in  this  transitional 
age  of  mental  and  material  anarchy. 

The  cosmological  system  of  Paracelsus,  for  with  meta- 
physic  he  did  not  occupy  himself,  was  based  on  the  con- 
ception of  the  tripartite  division  of  nature  and  man.  Nature 


PARACELSUS.  141 

was  the  macrocosm,  man  the  microcosm.  Man,  as  the 
pinnacle  of  nature,  embraced  in  his  body  the  elements  of 
all  other  things.  Without  astronomical,  physical  and 
theological  knowledge,  it  is  impossible  for  the  physician 
to  understand  the  true  nature  of  the  human  body  or  its 
diseases.  The  trinitarian  principle  was  all-pervading,  the 
prima  materia,  understanding  by  this  a  physical  substance, 
contains  within  it  the  potencies  of  all  things ;  but  even  in 
this  may  be  traced  a  triple  nature,  generally  designated  by 
Paracelsus  as  salt,  sulphur,  and  mercury,  though  sometimes 
as  Balsamum,  Besina,  and  Liquor.  Paracelsus  is  careful  to 
insist  he  does  not  mean  these  substances  in  the  gross  bodily 
form  presented  to  us,  but  their  spiritual  essences.  All 
material  things  contain  these  princij^les  ;  thus  in  wood  that 
which  forms  smoke  is  the  mercurial  princij)le,  that  which 
burns  is  the  sulphurous,  while  what  remains  as  ash  is  the 
saline.  In  man,  the  body  represents  salt,  the  animal  soul 
sulphur,  and  the  intellectual  principle  mercury.  In  the 
combination  and  separation  of  these,  the  variety  of  things 
aj^pears.  The  so-called  four  elements  as  we  know  them 
are  the  offspring  of  the  spirit  or  vulcanus  inhering  in 
them.  What  in  the  elements  is  vulcanus,  appears  in  com- 
posite individual  things  as  their  archeus,  or  individual 
force.  Man,  who  is  the  quintessence  of  all  things,  is  depen- 
dent upon  all :  his  intellect  is  divine,  his  animal  soul  astral, 
his  body  terrestrial.  Hence  his  state  in  sickness  can  only 
be  understood  by  referring  it  to  the  particular  element 
which  is  its  cause.  A  knowledge  of  water  and  earth  only 
gives  the  clue  to  the  body  of  man.  The  macrocosm 
embraces  heaven  as  well  as  earth,  and  to  man's  spiritual 
nature,  which  corresponds  to  the  former,  a  knowledge  of  the 
heavenly  bodies  is  requisite,  for  with  these  it  has  its  affinity. 
To  investigate  this  is  the  function  of  astrology.  The 
visible  stars  are  to  Paracelsus  only  the  body  (corpus)  of 
the  invisible  essences  which  animate  them.  But  it  is  need- 
less to  enter  further  into  the  details  of  Paracelsus'  system 
(if  it  can  be  termed  such),  with  its  sylphs,  gnomes,  kobbolds 
and  salamanders ;  its  far-fetched  and  fanciful  analogies ; 
its  strange  medley  of  Cabbalistic,  Platonic  and  Christian 
doctrines.  Its  key-note  is  the  corresj^ondence  between 
macrocosm  and  microcosm.     As  the  macrocosm  is  divided 


142        ALCHEMISTS   AND   COSMIC   SPECULATORS. 

into  its  upper  and  lower  parts  (the  heavens  and  the  earth),  - 
so  is  the  microcosm  into  body  and  animal  soul.  Outside 
these  spheres  which  constitute  the  subject-matter  of  human 
science  is  the  divine  order,  the  subject-matter  of  theology, 
the  divine  science.  To  this  belongs  the  rational  and  moral 
nature  of  man,  and  the  creative  activity  by  which  the 
universe  is  sustained  and  governed.  On  this  ground  human 
reason  is  inadequate,  and  revelation  (esoterically  inter- 
preted) is  the  only  guide.  A  point  that  strikes  one  in 
reading  Paracelsus  is  that  with  all  his  hatred  of  Aristotle 
and  Scholasticism,  he  is  unable  to  dispense  with  the  w^ell- 
known  Scholastic  distinctions  and  terminology.  The 
school-philosophy,  even  in  its  decay,  asserted  its  influence 
on  friends  and  foes  alike. 

It  is  an  apt  illustration  of  the  truth  of  what  we  before 
said  as  to  the  tendency  of  the  age,  that  much  the  same 
views  as  those  of  Paracelsus  were  enunciated  by  an 
Italian  contemporary,  also  a  physician,  who,  so  far  as  we  are 
aware,  had  no  knowledge  of  him  or  his  works.  Hierony- 
Mus  Cardanus  (or  Cardano,  as  it  is  in  Italian),  well-known 
for  his  interesting  and  curious  autobiography  entitled  De 
vita  propria,  was  born  in  1500,  at  Milan.  His  fame  as  a 
mathematician  and  scientific  investigator,  which  in  his 
own  day  was  great,  has  not  proved  enduring,  owing  to  the 
fact,  as  observed  by  a  recent  writer,  that  he  was  compelled 
to  labour,  "  partly  in  fields  of  research  where  no  important 
discovery  was  then  attainable,  partly  in  those  where  his 
discoveries  could  only  serve  as  the  stepping-stones  to  others 
by  which  they  were  inevitably  eclipsed."  Like  Paracelsus, 
Cardanus  was  an  ardent  believer  in  astrology,  which  he 
sought  to  establish  on  inductive  principles,  as  well  as  in 
the  "  occult  sciences "  generally.  His  two  philosophical 
treatises  are  entitled  respectively  De  subtilitate  rerum,  and 
De  varietate  rerum.  In  these,  as  we  have  said,  we  find  much 
the  same  order  of  speculation  as  in  the  works  of  Paracelsus  ; 
the  same  fanciful  analogies ;  the  same  subtle  afiinities ; 
the  same  haphazard  guesses.  The  "  elements  "  from  which, 
like  his  elder  contemporary^  Cardanus  excludes  that  of  fire, 
though  for  diiferent  reasons,  naturally  play  an  important 
part  in  his  system.  Even  the  elemental  spirits  and  other 
extra  human  intelligenci^s  assumed  by  Paracelsus,  are  to 


CARDANUS.  143 

bo  found  in  Cardanns.  At  the  same  time  there  are  re- 
markable glimpses  of  later  thought  which  open  out  now  and 
again  in  the  works  of  the  Italian.  Even  the  doctrine  of 
evolution  apjDears  in  a  crude  form,  while  the  truth  that 
the  end  of  man's  being  is  social  rather  than  personal,  is 
clearly  indicated  in  more  than  one  place.  Cardanus  is 
probably  the  first  wa-iter  who  hinted  at  the  idea  of  a  philo- 
sophy of  history.  In  fact,  the  whole  of  his  thought,  even 
where  most  fanciful,  tends  to  the  recognition  of  an  orderly 
sequence  in  events,  in  short,  of  the  prevalence  if  not  the 
universality  of  law,  in  every  sphere  of  existence.  Cardanus, 
who  was  also  a  great  traveller,  died  at  Eome  in  1576. 

Among  works  dealing  with  the  physical  speculations  of  the  sixteenth 
century  may  be  mentioned  Kixner  und  Siber's  Leben  und  Meinungen 
heruhmten  Fhysiker  im  \Qten  und  11  ten  Jahrhundert,  forming  a  part  of 
the  Gesrhichte  der  Physiologie.  Sprengel's  Geschichte  der  Arzeneikunde, 
Thiel  III. ;  Erdmann  deals  fully  with  thia  subject  in  Vol.  II.  of  his 
History. 


(    144    ) 

MODERN  PHILOSOPHY. 

FIRST  EPOCH,  A. 

THE  ABSTRACT-DOGMATIC  SYSTEMS. 

We  have  now  traced  briefly  the  development  of  specu- 
lative thought  from  its  rise  in  the  sixth  century  B.C. 
to  the  close  of  the  ancient  world  ;  we  have  seen  the  transi- 
tion of  philosophy  in  the  hands  of  the  Church  from 
its  ancient  forms  into  Scholasticism,  in  which  it  became 
the  slave  of  dogma ;  we  have  witnessed  the  decline  and 
fall  of  Scholasticism  at  the  Eenaissance,  and  its  replace- 
ment by  the  resuscitation  of  classical  systems,  through  the 
scholars  of  Italy,  and  the  crude  physical  speculations  of 
men  such  as  Agrippa,  Paracelsus,  and  Cardanus.  Hence- 
forth we  have  done  with  the  Middle  Ages,  and  enter  a 
period  with  which  current  thought  is  directly  affiliated  ; 
in  short,  the  period  of  Modern  Philosophy. 

We  noticed  that,  notwithstanding  their  declamations 
against  Aristotle  and  the  schoolmen,  the  writers  of  the 
Sixteenth  century  still  employed  scholastic  expressions  and 
folio ^ved  a  more  or  less  scholastic  order  of  thought.  The 
great  negative  characteristic  of  the  earlier  stages  of  the 
modern  period  (we  say  earlier  stages,  though  it  is  a 
characteristic  which  it  has  retained  in  some  of  its 
most  recent  developments)  is  the  entire  absence  of  all 
Aristotelean  terminology  and  method.  The  reaction 
against  scholasticism  had  at  last  done  its  work.  With 
the  quibbling  and  word-jugglery  of  the  schoolmen  were 
swept  away  the  all-important  distinctions  of  the  Stagirite 
himself.  But  philosophy  was  now  for  the  first  time  since 
the  earlier  Roman  Empire  more  or  less  independent,  not 
only  of  positive  dogma,  but  of  any  special  and  determinate 
intellectual  tendency.  In  the  Seventeenth  century  the 
foundations  of  modern  civilization  in  all  its  aspects  were 
laid ;  the  era  of  "  free  contract "  (so  called)  had  fairly 
dawned ;  the  hierarchy  of  the  Middle  Ages  was  spasmodic- 


Epoch  La.]      THE   ABSTRACT-DOGMATIC   SYSTEMS.         145 

ally  gasping  in  its  death-throes ;  authority  and  status  were 
undermined  in  all  directions ;  the  middle  class  was  assert- 
ing its  power  against  all  forms  of  feudal  domination  ;  the 
battle  between  Catholicism  and  Protestantism,  which  had 
raged  in  the  preceding  century  in  the  various  countries  of 
Europe,  was  now  practically  decided  one  way  or  the  other ; 
in  those  lands  where  the  middle  class  was  powerful, 
Protestantism  having  become  the  dominant  creed.  Philo- 
sophy, although  now  free  from  the  physical  persecution  of 
ecclesiasticism,  still  indirectly  felt  the  influence  of  dogma, 
an  influence,  however,  which  affected  it  less  and  less  as 
time  went  on,  while  the  oppression  it  exercised  was  more 
of  a  moral  and  social  than  a  legal  character. 

There  are  two  main  contemporary  streams  of  philosophic 
development  constituting  the  speculative  history  of  the 
Seventeenth  and  Eighteenth  centuries,  which  may  be 
termed  respectively  the  Abstract-Dogmatic  and  the  Em- 
pirical-Sceptical. The  reputed  founder  of  the  first  of  these 
lines  was  the  French  Descartes,  that  of  the  second  the 
English  Bacon.  The  Abstract-Dogmatic  schools  consist  (I.) 
of  the  Cartesians  proper,  (II.)  of  Spinoza  and  his  followers, 
and  (III.)  of  Leibnitz  and  those  who  drew  their  inspiration 
from  him,  such  as  the  Germans,  Wolff,  Baumgarten,  &c. 
The  Empirical-Sceptical  schools  embrace  the  names  of 
Bacon,  Hobbes,  Locke,  Berkeley,  Hume,  Eeid,  and  the 
Scotch  psychologists.  The  French  sensationists  and  ma- 
terialists of  the  Eighteenth  century  are  also  an  offshoot 
of  this  line  of  thought. 

The  Abstract-Dogmatic  schools  postulate  the  reality  out- 
side of  experience  oi  the  forms  of  thinJchig  which  alone  possess 
meaning  in  the  system  of  knowledge  or  experience.  They 
assume  concreteness  in  what  is  really  only  a  detached 
element  of  the  concrete  ;  they  assume,  that  is,  the  condi- 
tions of  the  whole  synthesis  as  present,  while  ex  JiyjyotJiesi 
they  are  making  abstraction  from  them. 

The  Empirical-Sceptical  schools  profoundly  ignore 
Metaphysic,  and  confine  themselves  to  psychology ;  yet 
they  in  the  long  run  usually  fall  into  the  metaphysical 
assumption  of  an  independent  external  world  as  the  cause 
of  the  individual  mind's  impressions.  The  next  step  is- 
Scepticism,  in  which  the  mere  individual  impression  or 

L 


146  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

idea  per  se  is  hypostasised ;  that  is,  made  the  ultimate 
reality.  In  Scepticism  the  bankruptcy  of  Empiricism 
becomes  manifest.  PhiloS'ophy  degenerates  into  a  mere 
negative  criticism.  There  is,  however,  one  way  of  escape, 
and  that  is  Materialism,  in  which  the  concrete  corpoieal 
substance  of  the  universe  is  made  al)Solute.  In  this 
doctrine  a  truth  is  presented,  though  inadequately, 
because  torn  from  its  connection.  It  is  nevertheless  the 
truth  of  Empiricism,  its  logical  and,  in  a  sense,  valid 
result. 


DESCARTES. 

Eene  Descartes  was  born  on  March  31st,  1596,  at  La 
Haye,  in  Touraine,  and  educated  in  the  Jesuit  College  of 
La  Fleche.  The  early  training  of  Descartes  in  mathe- 
matics and  philosophy  had  the  effect  for  many  years  to 
disgust  him  of  all  such  pursuits.  For  some  time  he 
occupied  himself  with  play  and  the  chase.  Subsequently 
he  entered  the  army  of  the  Netherlands  as  a  volunteer. 
During  this  portion  of  his  career  he  began  again  to 
interest  himself  in  intellectual  pursuits.  He  soon  ex- 
changed his  commission  in  the  army  of  the  Netherlands 
for  one  at  first  in  the  Bavarian,  and  afterwards  in  the 
Imperial  army  then  engaged  in  the  "  Thirty  Years'  War." 
It  was  now  that  Descartes  began  to  occupy  himself  in 
earnest  with  mathematical  investigations  chiefly  con- 
nected with  algebra  and  geometry.  He  shortly  after 
resigned  his  commission  and  devoted  himself  to  travel,  as 
a  private  individual,  visiting  in  succession  Holland, 
France,  Switzerland,  and  Italy.  He  afterwards  settled 
in  Holland,  occupying  himself  with  his  studies,  until  an 
invitation  from  Queen  Christina  of  Sweden  induced  him 
to  remove  to  Stockholm.  The  severity  of  the  climate 
proving  too  much  for  his  health,  never  very  robust,  he 
dned  on  the  11th  of  February,  1650,  in  the  last-named  city. 
The  principal  philosophical  Avorks  of  Descartes  are  his 
Trincipia  Philosophi.  his  3Ieditationes  de  prima  Philosopliia, 
his  earlier  Essais  Philosophiques,  and  his  short  treatise, 
the  Discours  sur  la  Methode, 


Epoch  I.a.]  DESCARTES.  14.7 


Descartes'  "Doctrines. 

The  system  of  Descartes  starts  from  the  celebrated 
'Methodic  Doubt,'  as  it  is  termed  by  his  followers. 
Descartes'  earlier  alienation  from  philosophy  had  been 
largely  due  to  the  loose  literary  spirit  of  scepticism  then 
prevalent  in  France  among  the  educated  classes,  and 
which  is  embodied  in  the  writings  of  Montaigne.  It  was 
clear,  therefore,  that  before  Descartes  could  enter  with 
any  zeal  upon  a  new  course  of  philosophic  investigation, 
he  must  make  up  his  account  with  the  scepticism  that, 
with  him  no  less  than  with  others,  had  discredited  the 
traditional  methods  of  the  schools,  methods  which  he  had 
satirically  characterised  as  affording  the  student  the 
means  of  "  talking  glibl}'  on  all  subjects  in  a  manner  to 
excite  the  wonder  of  the  less  instructed."  With  the 
object,  therefore,  of  forestalling  the  destructive  effects  of 
sceptical  arguments  on  the  system  he  hopes  to  rear,  he, 
so  to  speak,  inoculates  it  with  scepticism  at  birth. 

The  '  Methodic  Doubt,'  above  alluded  to,  forbade  any- 
thing to  be  taken  for  granted  that  could  possibly  be 
questi(  >ned.  But  could  not  everything  be  questioned  ? 
"  No,"  answers  Descartes,  the  evidences  of  the  senses  may  ; 
the  most  apparently  indestructible  declarations  of  the 
intellect  may ;  but  there  is  one  thing  which  all  doubt 
itself  presupposes,  and  that  is  the  doubter.  I  exist 
doubting,  but  doubting  is  only  a  form  of  thinking ;  there 
fore  this  is  as  much  as  to  say  I  exist  thinking.  Descartes' 
formula  for  this  fundamental  position  of  his  philosophy  is 
the  celebrated  Cogito  ergo  sum.  The  logical  form  of  this 
proposition  was  obviously  vulnerable,  and  Gassendi's 
criticism  of  it,  from  his  point  of  view,  undoubtedly 
justified.  But  the  form  of  statement  does  not  really  affect 
the  point  at  issue.  Descartes  wished  to  insist  upon  the 
intuitive  character  of  the  proposition,  "  I  am  conscious." 
In  this  he  regards  as  indistinguishable  the  fact  of 
existence  and  the  fact  of  consciousness,  of  the  matter, 
7,  and  the  form,  thought ,  a  circumstance  which,  as  we: 
shall   see  later  on,  has  had   a  bearing  on   the  Kantian 

L  2 


148  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. a. 

and  post-Kantian  philosophy  of  Germany.  Furnished 
with  this  primal  deliverance  of  consciousness,  Descartes 
thought  he  had  discovered  the  one  true  foundation  on 
which  j^hilosophy  can  stand.  The  Cogito  was  the  philo- 
sophic bantling  whose  system  had  been  purified  of 
debatable  matter,  such  as  might  subsequently  prove  soil 
for  scepticism,  by  the  lymph  of  the  "  Slethodic  Doubt." 
Here,  therefore,  was  the  criterion  of  truth,  all  that  stood 
or  fell  with  this  axiom  partook  of  its  certainty,  and 
partook  of  it  in  proportion  to  its  inseparability  from  the 
act  of  consciousness.  From  the  above  criterion  of  truth 
Descartes^j3^duces_jth^jth£Qrei^ 

conception  is  the  test  of  its  truth.  This,  however,  is 
limited  by  the  possibility  that  a  being  superior  to  myself 
might  deceive  me.  Hence  the  necessity  before  proceeding 
farther  of  determining  the  question  of  the  existence  and 
attributes  of  such  a  being. 

Now,  no  idea  which  obtains  in  the  mind  can  repre- 
sent more  than  the  object  from  which  it  is  formed  or 
which  causes  it.  Of  some  ideas,  as  for  instance  that  of 
a  doubting  or  thinking  being,  it  is  quite  clear  that  I 
might  have  them,  even  if  I  alone  existed  ;  for  I  myself 
should  be  their  prototype.  "  But  there  is  one  idea," 
proceeds  Descartes,  "  which  it  would  be  impossible  could 
arise  within  me  in  the  latter  case ;  to  wit,  the  idea  of 
an  infinite  Being.  This  I  can  neither  draw  from  my- 
self, since  I  am  finite,  nor  can  it  come  through  an 
abstraction  from  anything  finite  without  me."  I  can 
very  well  arrive  by  abstraction  at  the  conception  of  a 
negative  infinite,  in  other  words,  of  an  indefinite,  but  not 
at  the  positive  concej)tion  of  an  infinite  excluding  all 
limitation  whatever.  I  can  think,  for  instance,  of  an 
endless  space  by  abstracting  from  the  limits  of  the 
known  space.  But  this  is  infinite  only  in  a  particular 
sense,  it  is  not  absolutely  infinite.  Every  conception 
of  the  merely  negative  infinite,  the  infinite  of  one  kind 
only  (i.e.  the  indefinite)  presu^Dposes  that  of  the  positive 
infinite.  The  latter  idea  it  is  not  in  my  power  to 
diminish  by  the  abstraction  or  to  increase  by  the  ad- 
dition of  anything,  and  conseqnentl}^,  says  Descartes, 
"  nothing  remains  but  to  admit  this  idea  as  coeval  with 


Epoch  I.a.]  DESCARTES.  149 

my  creation,  in  other  words,  as  co-extensive  witli  the  idea 
of  myself." 

The  presence  of  the  idea  of  the  infinite  within  ns  demon- 
strates, according  to  Descartes,  the  existence  of  an  infinite 
Being  without  us  who  is  its  original,  and  who  has  Himself 
implanted  it  in  us.  Even  viewing  the  matter  a  posteriori,  I 
should  require  a  cause,  though  I  existed  from  eternity, 
for  without  it  I  could  not  continue  in  existence.  To  be 
maintained  in  existence  is  to  be  continuously  re-created. 
But  the  argument  for  the  existence  of  God  upon  which 
Descartes  most  plumes  himself  is  his  celebrated  "onto- 
logical "  argument.  The  existence  of  God,  according  to  this 
i&rgument,  must  be  drawn  from  his  very  conception  itself ; 
for  inasmuch  as  the  idea  of  a  triangle  contains  that  of 
three  sides,  so  does  the  idea  of  the  Infinite  contain  that  of 
necessary  existence,  since  contingent  existence  would 
imply  dependence  or  limitation  and  therefore  contradict 
the  notion  of  infinity.  Descartes  distinguishes  his  onto- 
logical  argument  from  the  somewhat  similar  one  of 
Anselm  by  the  remark  that  it  does  not  rest  simply 
upon  the  mere  significance  of  a  word,  u]3on  the  fact 
that  we  conceive  God  as  existent — since  all  we  think  of, 
in  so  far  as  we  think  of  it,  is  thought  of  as  existing — 
but  upon  the  necessity  which  attaches  to  the  thought  of 
existence  in  this  particular  case,  and  upon  the  fact  that 
this  thought  is  not  a  mere  figment  of  the  mind,  but  a 
necessary,  because  innate,  idea. 

The  existence  of  God  is  the  second  position  in  the 
Cartesian  construction.  "  Self"  and  "  God  "  satisfactorily 
accounted  for,  the  next  proceeding  is  to  establish  the 
existence  of  the  "  World."  Descartes  having  found  as  the 
ultimate  postulate  of  his  philosophy  the  clear  and  de- 
terminate conception  of  himself  as  a  thinking  being,  and 
having  proclaimed  clearness  of  perception  the  test  of 
truth,  barring  the  possibility  of  deception  from  a  superior 
being,  next  proceeded  to  determine  the  existence  and  the 
nature  of  this  being.  In  the  course  of  the  investigation, 
the  notion  of  an  infinite  being  was  shown  to  exclude  all 
limitation  and  all  imperfection  of  any  kind  whatever,  in 
other  words,  to  involve  the  notion  of  absolute  perfec- 
tion.     But  the   deception  is   irreconcilable   with   moral 


150  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. a. 

perfection,  and  hence  must  be  excluded  from  our  con- 
ception of  divinity.  Yet  were  it  the  case  that  our  per- 
ceptions which  appear  to  represent  an  existent  world  did 
not  really  do  so,  we  should  be  compelled  to  assume  de- 
ception, i.e.  moral  imperfection,  in  our  Infinite  Author. 
The  canon  is  therefore  now  established  without  reserve, 
that  that  of  which  we  have  a  clear  perception  exists.  To 
the  objection  that  the  above  argument  proves  too  much, 
since  it  precludes  the  possibility  of  human  error,  Descartes 
replies,  that  error  does  not  consist  merely  in  the  imperfect 
apprehension  of  things  per  se,  but  in  the  individual's  act 
of  will  by  which  that  imperfect  apprehension  is  accepted 
as  true.  In  this  connection  he  draws  a  distinction  between 
the  unsophisticated  thought  which  instinctively  accepts 
the  dictates  of  common-sense  without  hesitation  (e.g.  the 
belief  in  external  objects),  and  the  thought  which  comes 
of  reflection  and  which  is  voluntary. 

Now  that  the  validity  of  his  canon  of  investigation 
has  been  settled,  Descartes  naturally  proceeds  more  quickly 
in  the  construction  of  his  system.  He  distinguishes 
between  those  conceptions  which  pre-suppose,  i.e.  are 
limitations  of,  other  conceptions  or  ideas,  and  those  which 
are  independent,  or  which  are  conceived  per  se.  The  only 
ideas  which  are  capable  of  being  conceived  per  se,  Descartes 
finds  to  be  those  "of  extension  and  thought.  Each  of  these 
can  be  thought  of  without  the  assistance  of  the  other  or 
of  any  foreign  idea  whatsoever  except  that  of  infinity. 
These  independent  self-existent  ideas,  Descartes  terms 
attrihuta,  which  he  derives  from  the  etymology  a  natura 
tributa  sunt.  The  former  class  of  ideas — those  which  are 
derivative,  that  is,  are  merely  limitations  of  other  ideas 
— he  terms  modi.^  Although  extension  and  thought  are  the 
only  attrihuta  of  things  known  to  us,  Descartes  declares 
that  in  God,  in  whom  of  course  there  are  necessarily  no 
modi,  inasmuch  as  these  would*  imply  limitation,  "  the 
attributes  are  many."  This  portion  of  Descartes'  system 
is  especially  important  in  its  bearing  on  Spinoza.  In 
this  respect  also  Descartes'  definition  of  the  independent 
subjects  of  the  attributes,  which  he  terms  substances,  is 
particularly  noteworthy.  A  substance,  says  Descartes, 
is  "  that  which  requires  nothing  else  to  its  being  or  con- 


Epoch  La.]  DESCARTES.  151 

ception;"  in  otlier  words,  it  is  an  absolutely  independent 
existence  ;  for,  as  ho  expressly  asserts,  an  incomplete  sub- 
stance is  a  contradiction.  Still  further  remarkable  is  it 
that  (in  his  Principia)  he  actual  1}^  touches  Spinozism  in 
conceding  that,  according  to  the  literal  terms  of  his  defini- 
tion, there  could  only  be  one  substance,  namely,  God.  He 
gets  over  this  somewhat  inconsequently  by  extending  the 
definition  as  regards  the  supposed  created  substances  in 
which  the  attributes  of  extension  and  thought  are  assumed 
to  inhere,  namely  mind  and  matter,  by  declaring  that  though 
not  absolutely  independent,  inasmuch  as  they  have  their 
ground  in  the  Supreme  Being,  yet  they  are  relatively  so, 
that  is,  as  regards  all  other  created  things.  The  existence 
of  body  (^matter)  and  mind,  as  substances,  Descartes  finds 
guaranteed  by  his  conception  of  them  as  such,  and  a 
fortiori,  by  the  trustworthiness  of  the  Deity.  Inasmuch 
as  they  are  substances  they  mutually  exclude  each  other. 
TJiought  is  pure  inwardness,  having  no  analogy  whatever 
with  extension,  which  is  pure  outwardness.  There  can  be 
no  question  of  any  community  between  them.  This 
extreme  dualism  was  the  rock  upon  which  Cartesianism 
split.  It  is  true  Descartes  thereby  separates  himself  from 
Spinoza,  but  he  also  logicall}'-  separates  himself  from 
Leibnitz,  although  there  are  not  wanting  indications  in 
his  works  of  a  tendency,  at  times,  to  Leibnitzianism. 

The  practical  consequence  of  the  dualistic  character  of 
Descartes'  metaphysics  is,  that  the  two  departments  of 
physics  and  psychology  are  entirely  severed  from  one 
another.  Descartes  always  regarded  his  physics  as  the 
most  important  part  of  his  work.  Its  problem  was  to 
formulate  all  that  can  be  discovered  in  nature  by  reflec- 
tion thereupon.  In  this,  it  is  clear,  abstraction  must  be 
made  from  the  sensuous  qualities  of  objects,  for  these 
sensuous  qualities  are  no  more  than  states  or  feelings  of 
the  perceiving  mind,  which  have  as  much  resemblance  to 
that  which  causes  the  feeling  as  mere  words  have  with 
the  ideas  of  which  they  are  the  signs  :  "  All  the  sensuous 
qualities  of  things  lie  in  us,  i.e.  in  the  soul,"  Descartes 
repeatedly  insists.  Hence  physical  investigation  demands 
that  we  abstract  from  all  that  does  not  pertain  to  the 
objects   themselves,  or  to  the  modes  by  which  they  are 


152  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. a. 

related  to"  us,  as  for  instance  time,  mimber,  &c.  The  only 
quality  whicli,  according  to  Descartes,  inheres  in  bodies 
themselves  is  extension  in  its  three  dimensions  of  length, 
breadth,  and  thickness.  Space  and  matter  are  coextensive, 
an  emj)ty  space  involving  a  contradiction.  Descartes 
maintains  extension  as  the  sole  quality  of  matter  per  se,  not 
even  excluding  gravity.  The  result  of  this  is  that  he 
was  enabled  to  identify  physics  with  mathematics,  and  to 
claim  for  his  physical  doctrine  the  certitude  of  geometry. 
In  accordance  with  this  view,  he  excludes  all  idea  of 
purpose  in  nature  from  his  investigations.  He,  of  course, 
did  not  deny  divine  purpose  in  the  world,  but  declared 
speculation  with  regard  to  it  impious.  All  which  follows 
from  the  conception  of  extension,  and  nothing  but  this,  is 
to  be  affirmed  respecting  this  corporeal  world.  Hence 
there  'are  neither  atoms  nor  limits  in  the  world.  The 
capacity  of  division,  of  figure,  and  of  motion,  is  comprised 
in  the  conception  of  extension.  To  their  realisation  these 
capacities  require  a  cause  outside  themselves,  which  cause 
is  God.  The  first  principle  of  realisation  is  motion ;  the 
variety  of  bodies  consists  in  nothing  but  the  different 
motions  of  themselves  or  their  parts.  A  curious  anticipa- 
tion of  modern  thought  is  seen  in  Descartes'  principle  of 
the  constancy  of  the  sum  of  matter  and  motion  in  the 
universe. 

In  his  Monde,  a  work  containing  his  theories  on  physical 
science  proper,  he  starts  with  the  hypothesis  of  a  new 
world  to  be  created  on  mechanical  and  mathematical  princi- 
ples alone.  In  this  he  furnishes  many  interesting  anticipa- 
tions of  modern  science,  in  addition,  as  might  be  exjDected, 
to  many  untenable  hypotheses,  such,  for  instance,  as  the 
celebrated  "  theory  of  vortices,"  and  some  of  his  theories 
respecting  physiology,  though  in  this  department  he  also 
achieved  some  valuable  results.  Animal  bodies,  including 
the  human,  he  regarded,  in  accordance  with  his  funda- 
mental physical  principles,  as  purely  automatic.  It  is  the 
psychical  principle,  or  soul,  in  man,  which  alone  distin- 
guishes him  from  the  lower  animals. 

This  leads  us  to  the  Cartesian  Psychology,  or  doctrine  of 
the  soul.  As  the  attribute  of  body  is  extension,  so  the 
attribute  of  soul  is  thought ;  just  as  the  material  substance, 


Epoch  I.a.]  DESCARTES.  153 

inasmuch  as  extension  is  its  attribute,  can  neither  exist 
nor  be  conceived  without  extension;  so  tbe  mental  sub- 
stauce  whose  attribute  is  thought,  can  neither  be  con- 
ceived nor  exist  apart  from  thought.  The  soul  is  always 
conscious — always  thinks — ^just  as  light  always  illumines, 
as  heat  always  warms,  &c.  Even  the  babe  in  the  womb 
is  conscious.  There  is  no  such  thing  as  dreamless  sleep ; 
it  is  merely  memory  failing  us,  which  leads  us  to  think  this 
possible,  and  memory,  Descartes  is  careful  to  remind  the 
reader,  is  a  purely  bodily  state. 

Descartes  divides  ideas  as  concerns  their  clearness  into 
adequate  and  inadequate,  or  complete  and  incomplete ;  as 
concerns  their  origin,  into  self-made  ideas  (fictse),  into  bor- 
rowed ideas  (adveatitise),  and  inborn  ideas  (innatse).  The 
will  is  always  dependent  on  consciousness,  that  is,  on  an 
act  of  perception ;  but  there  may  be  acts  of  perception 
apart  from  any  act  of  will.  Error  consists  in  the  affirma- 
tion by  the  will  as  true  of  an  inadequate  perception  or 
idea.  Hence,  in  God,  in  whom  is  no  inadequate  idea, 
error  is  impossible.  In  the  latter  case  truth  consists  in 
his  affirmation  of  it,  in  the  fact  that  he  wills  such  and  such 
to  be  true.  In  the  same  way  goodness  is  purely  determined 
by  the  Divine  will.  Truth  and  goodness  are,  therefore,  with 
Descartes,  dependent  in  the  last  resort  solely  on  the  arbi- 
trary fiat  of  a  supreme  being.  Descartes,  of  course,  maintains 
the  freedom  of  the  human  will,  but  at  the  same  time  regards 
indeterminateness  as  the  lowest  stage  of  willing.  He  who 
possessed  clear  and  distinct  ideas  of  the  good  and  the  true, 
would  never  hesitate  in  choosing  it,  and  hence  would  not 
be  indifferent.  The  highest  freedom  and  the  highest 
perfection  obtains,  when  error  has  become  impossible 
through  knowledge.  The  Sokratic  doctrine  thus  once 
more  appears  in  the  history  of  ethical  speculation. 

When  Descartes  comes  to  speak  of  Anthropology,  that  is, 
of  man,  as  a  personality  in  which  thought  and  extension 
appear  in  union,  his  dualism  naturally  gives  him  some 
trouble.  The  union  he  declares  to  constitute  only  a 
composition,  which  is  purely  empirical,  resting  upon  a  super- 
natural fact,  that  is  a  special  act  of  the  Divine  will.  Al- 
though the  soul  is  in  union  with  the  whole  body,  this  union 
is  effected  immediately  by  means  of  a  specific  organ,  to 


15 J:  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

wit,  tlie  pineal  gland,  which  according  to  Descartes,  is  the 
source  of  the  '  animal  spirits,'  and  for  this  and  sundry 
other  fanciful  reasons  the  most  suitable  seat  for  it.  On 
the  above  theory,  Descartes  proceeds  to  explain  the  effects 
of  the  emotions  and  passions.  The  contest  of  the  mind 
with  the  appetites  is  not  one  between  a  higher  and  a  lower 
soul,  but  between  the  soul  and  the  so-called  '  nervous  fluids' 
or  '  animal  spirits.'  The  practical  side  of  Descartes'  ethics 
falls  to  be  dealt  with  in  this  connection.  The  most  im- 
portant point,  however,  in  his  anthropological  doctrine, 
for  the  subsequent  history  of  the  Cartesian  school,  is  the 
virtual  assumption  of  a  perpetual  miracle  in  the  union 
of  body  and  soul. 

In  the  foregoing  pages  we  have  endeavoured  to  give 
a  clear  general  view  of  the  Cartesian  system  as  it  left 
the  hands  of  its  founder.  Its  strength  and  its  weakness 
will  appear  in  the  course  of  the  succeeding  historic  de- 
velopment. Criticism  is  unnecessary  of  a  doctrine  which 
the  average  educated  reader  will  now-a-days  readily  see 
is  fatally  vulnerable  in  many  of  its  cardinal  principles. 
The  sceptical  attitude  assumed  at  starting  gives  way,  after 
the  first  stage  in  the  construction  has  been  reached,  to  so 
much  obvious  sophistry  even  in  essentials,  that  whether 
they  be  right  or  wrong  in  fact,  we  can  hardly  wonder  at 
the  attitude  of  those  critics  who  have  regarded  it  as  a 
*'  blind,"  consciously  put  forward  to  guard  certain  vulner- 
able points  in  the  coming  construction  which  had  been  in 
reality  assumed  from  the  first.  Facilis  ascensus  coeli,  to  the 
aspiring  philosopher.  But  be  this  as  it  may,  Descartes' 
position,  as  the  founder  of  modern  philosophy,  is  not  to  be 
gainsaid.  Of  a  rather  feeble  moral  nature,  he  lived  in  a 
continual  dread  of  unpleasant  notice  being  taken  of  him 
by  the  Church ;  his  obsequiousness  in  this  respect  being 
remarked  even  in  an  age  of  theological  subservience. 
This  makes  it  difficult  in  estimating  Descartes  and  his 
work,  to  determine  in  some  cases  whether  a  particular 
doctrine  is  to  be  attributed  to  mental  servility  or  real 
conviction.  But  the  historian  of  philosophy  must  console 
himself  with  the  maxim  chacun  a  les  defauts  de  ses  qualites. 

Cartesianism,  thougb  in  the  end  successful  all  along  the 


Epoch  I. a.]  MALEBRANCHE.  155 

line,  did  not  pass  without  encountering  a  brisk  fire  of 
adverse  criticism.  Descartes  himself  formally  replied  to 
the  more  important  objections  raised  against  his  system  in 
a  separate  work.  Amongst  the  critics  with  whom  he  deals 
w.ere  Hobbes  and  Locke;  for  in  addition  to  objections  from 
the  side  of  Scholasticism,  and  the  resuscitated  Greek  phi- 
losophy of  the  Eenaissance,  Descartes  had  to  encounter 
the  contemporary  British  movement.  The  new  system 
made  its  way  notwithstanding.  The  university  of  Utrecht, 
in  Holland,  was  the  first  official  home  of  Cartesianism. 
But  in  Leyden  we  find  the  most  brilliant  series  of  teachers, 
foremost  among  whom  is  Geulincx.  The  other  Dutch 
universities  soon  caught  the  infection,  and  Holland,  which 
had  long  been  the  home  of  Descartes  himself,  became 
the  principal  seed-ground  of  his  philosophy.  Clerical 
opposition,  more  or  less  successful,  there  was,  of  course,  but 
this  in  the  long  run  rather  helped  than  hindered  its  ger- 
mination. In  theology,  in  medicine,  in  physical  science, 
Cartesianiam  became  the  order  of  the  day  throughout 
Western  Europe,  Great  Britain  excepted.  The  philoso^^hy 
of  Descartes  was  not  wdthout  its  influence  on  the  decadence 
in  the  belief  in  magic,  witchcraft,  and  the  "  occult  sciences," 
which  took  place  so  rapidly  among  the  educated  towards 
the  close  of  the  century.  Belthasar  Bekker  published 
in  1691  his  celebrated  work  'The  Enchanted  World,' 
in  which  he  attacked  these  superstitions  on  Cartesian ' 
grounds.  This  treatise,  originally  written  in  Dutch,  had 
not  been  published  long  before  it  was  translated  into  all 
the  more  important  European  languages. 

The  celebrated  Port-Royal  Logic  (L'art  de  penser)  was 
perhaps  the  principal  product  of  Cartesianism  in  the  land 
of  its  founder's  birth,  upon  the  culture  of  which  it  made 
a  deep  impression. 

MALEBRANCHE. 

The  first  successor  of  Descartes  who  can  be  regarded  as 
having  at  all  developed  the  master's  doctrines  was  the 
Erench  ecclesiastic,  Nicholas  Malebranche,  born  at  Paris 
in  1638.  His  BecJierche  de  la  verite,  first  published  in  1674, 
passing  through  six  editions  during  the  lifetime  of  its 


156  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. a. 

author.  It  was  followed  by  a  large  mimber  of  treatises^ 
metaphysical,  theological,  and  ethical,  up  to  the  time  of 
the  death  of  Malebranche,  iu  1715. 

The  main  problem  for  Malebranche  was  to  bridge  over 
the  gulf  between  the  two  opposed  substances  of  Descartes' 
Thought  and  Extension  ;  to  define  their  relation  alike  to  the 
finite  individual  and  their  infinite  ground.  Malebranche 
was  not  satisfied  with  the  hesitating  and  superficial  manner 
in  which  Descartes  had  attempted  to  explain  away  the 
difficulties  which  arose  on  this  head.  The  arbitrary  act  of 
the  Divine  will  by  which  perception  was  produced  was  too 
clumsy  an  hypothesis  for  him.  The  celebrated  saying  of 
Malebranche,  that  he  saw  "  all  things  in  God,"  of  itself 
indicates  the  link  between  the  dualism  of  Descartes  and 
the  Pantheism  of  Spinoza.  To  the  former  the  relation  of 
the  two  subordinate  substances  alike  to  each  other  and  to 
the  one  infinite  substance  was  indefinite  and  arbitrary. 
Malebranche  sought  to  give  that  relation  a  systematic  basis. 
Starting  from  the  conception  of  the  Infinite  Being,  which 
Descartes  had  formulated,  he  brought  Thought  and  Extension^ 
and  through  them  Individuation,  nearer  this  being,  deduced 
them  more  directly  from  this  being  than  Descartes  had 
dared  to  do.  Unlike  Descartes,  he  does  not  separate  the 
idea  or  notion,  from  the  existence,  of  the  infinite.  "  We 
conceive  of  the  infinite  being,"  says  Malebranche,  "by  the 
very  fact  of  our  conceiving  of  being  without  thinking 
whether  it  be  finite  or  not ;  but  that  we  may  think  of  a 
finite  being  we  are  compelled  to  sever  or  deduct  something 
from  the  general  idea  of  being,  which  we  must  therefore 
possess  beforehand ;  thus,  the  mind  apprehends  nothing 
whatever  except  in  and  through  the  idea  it  possesses  of 
the  infinite ;  so  far  is  it  from  the  truth  that  this  idea  is 
formed  by  the  confused  mass  of  our  notions  of  particular 
things,  as  the  philosophers  maintain,  that  on  the  other  hand, 
all  these  particular  notions  participate  in  the  general  idea  of 
the  infinite,  in  the  same  way  that  all  crea1;ures  imperfectly 
participate  in  the  Divine  being,  whose  existence  itself 
cannot  be  derived  from  them."  (^Becherche  III.,  Part  IL, 
Chap.  6).  The  external  world  is  unintelligible  in  itself, 
and  only  becomes  intelligible  by  our  perceiving  it  in  and 
through  the   being   who   contains  it  in  an  intelligible 


Epoch.  I.a.]  SPINOZA.  157 

manner.  "Hence,"  says  Malebranche,  "unless  in  some 
sense  we  saw  God,  we  shonld  see  nothing  else."  In  short, 
our  consciousness,  whether  of  ourselves  or  of  external 
objects,  is  nothing  more  nor  less  than  a  limited  portion  of 
the  divine  consciousness.  From  this  doctrine  of  Male- 
branche  of  all  "  things  in  God "  to  the  imica  substantia 
of  Spinoza  was  scarcely  a  step.  The  only  modus  viiencli 
between  TJiougJit  and  Extension,  mind  and  body,  was  found 
in  the  divine  essence  or  substance ;  but  Malebranche  not 
merely  shrank  from  the  obvious  conclusion  to  which  all 
bis  reasoning  points,  that  of  identifying  them  with  the 
substance,  but,  strange  to  say  (that  is,  strange  were  it  not 
so  common  a  phenomenon  in  history),  denounces  in  scurri- 
lous language  the  man  who  was  at  once  honest  and  logical 
enough  to  draw  this  conclusion. 


SPINOZA. 

Baruch  de  Spinoza,  born  Nov.  24,  1632,  at  Amsterdam, 
belonged  to  a  well-to-do  Jewish  family  of  Portuguese 
origin  settled  in  Holland.  He  received  a  thorough  educa- 
tion in  the  hands  of  the  Eabbis  of  his  native  town  in  all 
that  pertained  to  Jewish  learning  as  then  understood, 
besides  studying  Latin  and  natural  science,  under  other 
teachers.  Previous  reading  of  the  semi-rationalising  Jewish 
philosophers  of  the  Middle  Ages,  notably  Maimonides,  had 
already  given  Spinoza  a  speculative  groundwork  when 
he  took  up  the  study  of  the  works  of  Descartes.  Spinoza 
occupies  a  unique  position  at  this  time.  His  heterodoxy 
had  already  caused  his  expulsion  from  the  synagogue,  and 
he  thus  found  himself  unpledged  to  any  set  of  traditional 
dogmas.  To  this  fact  we  may  attribute  the  perfect  freedom 
and  honesty  displayed  in  his  writings.  The  fawning  of 
Descartes  to  Christian  doctrines  naturally  disgusted  the 
man  w^ho  had  severed  himself  from  family  connections, 
social  intercourse,  and  even  risked  life  itself  for  his  convic- 
tions. But,  nevertheless,  the  system  of  Spinozat^is._±]ie 
direct_and  logical  outcome  oftEe  principles  enunciated  b^ 
l5escartes.  After~a  generally  ^quiet  and"  uneventful  life, 
occupied  either  in   the  pursuance  of  his  livelihood  as  a 


158  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

glass-lens  polisher,  or  in  study  and  wi-iting,  Spinoza  died 
at  the  comparatively  early  age  of  forty-five,  in  the  year 
1677.  The  respect  with  which  he  was  regarded  by  all  who 
knew  him  is  illustrated  in  the  well-known  story  of  his 
landlady,  who,  aware  that  he  belonged  to  no  recognised 
religious  persuasion,  asked  his  opinion  as  to  whether  she 
wa-s  justified  in  going  to  Church  and  otherwise  practising 
the  rites  of  the  orthodox  Calvinistic  faith.  He  had  com- 
paratively but  few  friends,  but  among  these  several  corre- 
spondents, notably  Oldenburg,  one  of  the  founders  of  the 
English  Koyal  Society. 

Spinoza's  Doctrines. 

With  Spinoza  ^the  method  ,of  philosophy  if=t  identical 
with  that  of  mathematics.  In  his  Ethics  he  places  Defini- 
tions, Axioms,  and  Postulates,  at  the  head  of  every  book. 
The  Geometrical  method  appeared  to  him  as  the  aiost 
'grji^nijj^br  the"  expression  ot  ^^  clear  ana  aistinct  ^'  ideas, 
and  as^  the  one  wnich  mosx  etfectually  excluded  the 
possibility  of  the  entrance  into  philosophy  of  personal  or 
other  bias — it  was  the  only  purely  disinterested  method. 

Hegel  observes,  that  Spinoza,  the  Jew,  first^  mtroduced 
into  European  thought  the  conception  of  thG.^a3liSju2i35^ 
in  Avhich  finite  and  infinite  are  merged.  It  would  be  per- 
haps more  correct"  to  say  that  he  was  the  first  to  give  dis- 
tinct expression  to  this  j^gjjjs^bDointo^jjigw,  which  is 
ynplicitly  present  in  many  previous  tniiTtCCTgr"^ 

Spinoza  distinguishes  two  kinds  of  errors  to  which  the 
mind  is  subject,  those  of  ahstraction  and  those  oi  imagination. 
These  two  errors  he  finds  invariably  united  in  opinion.  An 
abstraction  means  any  imperfect  conception  in  which 
the  elements  of  a  whole  are  separately  treated  as  wholes. 
Clear  and  distinct  thought  must  discern  the  necessary 
relation  of  any  finite  thing  or  notion  to  the  whole  system 
of  things  or  notions.  This  is  expressed  in  Spinc)zistic 
language  by  what  is  termed  the  distinction  between  mere 
modes  of  substance  and  substance  itself.  The  progress  of 
knowledge  necessarily  limits  this  abstracting  tendency. 
Imagination  comes  to  the  aid  of  abstraction  in  enabling 
^ae  mind  to  picture  the  thing  without  its  surroundings,  or 


Erocii  I.A.]  SPINOZA.  159 

in  other  words,  apart  from  the  conditions  necessary  to  its 
real  existence.  Such  coucei)tions  as  that  of  a  talking 
animal,  a  horse  with  a  man's  head,  an  extended  figure 
without  weight  or  resistance,  are  common  and  obvious 
instances  of  this  combined  power  of  abstraction  and  imag- 
ination. Teleological  explanations  of  the  world  have  their 
root  entirely  in  the  foregoing  tendency  of  the  mind.  "  All 
such  oiuuions,"  says  Spinoza,  "  spring  from  the  notion, 
commonly  entertained,  that  all  things  in  nature  act  for  the 
same  reason  as  men  themselves  act,  with  an  end  in  view." 
Human  will  and  action  are  abstracted  from  the  only  whole 
of  which  they  can  form  a  part,  namely  the  human  being, 
and  transferred  by  the  imagination  to  external  nature,  and 
even  the  Absolute  itself.  The  consequence  of  this  is 
exhibited  in  religion,  in  the  anthropomorphic  conception 
of  God  as  having  "  made  all  things  for  man,  and  man 
that  he  might  worship  Him."  Jn  the  Appendix  to  the  first 
book  of  the  Ethics,  Spinoza  demolishes  this  view  with  hij 
usual  clearness  and  vigour. 

In  philosophy  ^^inoza  demands  the  elimination  of  all_ 
Uiiie-i'elations,  in  other  words,  that  the  philosopher  should 
be  unaerstooa  as  viewing  the  world  sub  specie  aeternitatis. 
Bj^  this,  of  course,  he  meant  that  the  province  of  meta- 
physic  is  to  expound  the  world  in  its  logical,  rather  than 
its  temporal  sequence.  Hence,  the  starting-point  of  his 
system  is  not  any  first  cause  of  all  things  in  the  ordinary 
sense  of  the  word,  but  that  which  all  -things  Ipgiea^ly  pre- 
sujrmse ;  that  by  mearisoF  which  all  other  things  are  con- 
ceived,  but  which  is  in  itself  indej[3endent  and  ultimate*^ 

In  this  great  advanT?g''g^niMeonr"I)escartes,  whose  God 
was  little  more  than  the  firslTcause  of  the  worlds  This  un- 
coj3^itioned__ground,  the  one  substance  of  Spinoza,  mntaTns 


within  Tt  the  sum-total  of  all  reality.  Although  he  did 
homage  to  current  prejudices  by  emplt>ying  the  word  God 
for  his  conception,  it  is  only  fair  to  remember  that  he  dis- 
tinctly disclaims  using  the  word  in  any  current  sense. 

Erdmann  well  observes  that  those  who  connect  the  usual 
religious  significance  with  the  word  God,  had  better,  in 
reading  Spinoza,  substitute  for  it  the  word  Nature.  It  is 
constantly  insisted  upon  that  all  things  proceed  from  the 
One  Substance  by  the  same  necessity  as  that  by  which  it 


160  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a, 

exists,  since  they  form  an  essential  part  of  its  existence. 
Of  the  infinite  attributes  of  the  infinite,  eternal,  and  aU- 
comprehending  substance,  two  only  concern  us,  i.e.  Thought 
and  Extension.  As  Ydth  Descartes,  they  are  mutually 
opposed  in  every  respect,  in  all  save  the  one  fact  of  their 
common  ground.  At  last  the  Cartesian  problem  is  solved 
in  the  only  way  possible  on  Cartesian  principles.  Thought 
and  Extension,  Mind  and  Body,  assume  for  the  first  time  a 
position  of  mutual  equality ;  while  they  at  the  same  time 
lose  the  last  shred  of  their  independence  of  the  Infinite. 
The  real  w^orld  is  simply  made  up  of  modes  of  these  two 
attributes.  By  mode,  Spinoza  understands  that  which 
exists  through  something  else,  or  which  is  the  determi- 
nation of  something  else.  There  are  eternal  modes,  by 
which  is  probably  meant  the  necessary  determinations  of 
things  termed  by  us  laws  of  nature,  and  individual  or 
finite  things.  As,  however,  the  place  of  individuals  in 
Spinoza's  system  is  not  unobscure,  we  give  some  of  his 
utterances  on  this  head  in  his  own  words.  In  Proposition 
XXIII.  of  Part  I.  of  the  Ethics,  we  read,  "  Every  mode,  which 
exists  both  necessarily  and  as  infinite  must  necessarily  follow 
either  from  the  absolute  nature  of  some  attribute  of  God  or 
from  an  attribute  modified  by  a  modification  ivhich  exists 
necessarily  and  as  infinite.  Proof.  A  mode  exists  in  some- 
thing else  through  which  it  must  be  conceived  (Def.  v.), 
that  is  (Prop,  xv.),  it  exists  solely  in  God,  and  solely  through 
God  can  be  conceived.  If,  therefore,  a  mode  is  conceived  as 
necessarily  existing,  and  infinite,  it  must  necessarily  be 
inferred  or  perceived  through  some  attribute  of  God,  in  so 
far  as  such  attribute  is  conceived  as  exj^ressing  the  infinity 
and  necessity  of  existence,  in  other  words  (Def.  viii.), 
eternally  ;  that  is,  in  so  far  as  it  is  considered  absolutely." 
"  A  mode  therefore  which  necessarily  exists  as  infinite  must 
follow  from  the  absolute  nature  of  some  attribute  of  God, 
either  immediately  (Prop,  xxi.),  or  through  the  means  of 
some  modification  which  follows  from  the  absolute  nature 
of  the  said  attribute ;  that  is  (by  Prop,  xxii.)  which  exists 
necessarily  and  as  infinite  (Prop.  xxiv.).  The  essence  of 
things  produced  by  God  does  not  involve  existence.  Proof.  This 
proi30sition  is  evident  from  Def.  i.  For  that  of  which  the 
nature  considered  in  itself  involves  existence  is  self-caused. 


Erocii  I. A.]  SPINOZA.  IGl 

and  exists  by  the  sole  necessity  of  its  own  nature. 
Corollary.  Uence,  it  follows  that  God  is  not  only  the 
cause  of  things  coming  into  existence,  but  also  of  their 
continuing  in  existence,  that  is,  in  scholastic  phraseology, 
God  is  cause  of  the  being  of  things  (Esseiicli  rerum).  For 
whether  things  exist  or  do  not  exist,  whenever  we  contem- 
plate their  essence,  we  see  that  it  involves  neither  existence 
nor  duration ;  consequently  it  cannot  be  the  cause  of  either 
the  one  or  the  other.  God  must  be  the  sole  cause,  in  as  much 
as  to  Him  alone  does  existence  appertain.  (Prop.  xiv. 
Corollary  1.)  Q.E.D.  (Prop,  xxv.)  God  is  the  efficient  cause 
not  only  of  the  existence  of  things  hut  also  of  their  essence. 
Proof.  If  this  be  denied,  then  God  is  not  the  cause  of  the 
essence  of  things  ;  and  therefore,  the  essence  of  things  can 
(by  Ax.  IV.)  be  conceived  without  God,  This  by  Prop.  xv. 
is  absurd.  Therefore  God  is  the  cause  of  the  essence  of 
things.  Q.E.D.  Note.  This  proposition  follows  more 
clearly  from  Prop.  xvi.  for  it  is  evident  thereby,  that 
given  the  Divine  nature,  the  essence  of  things  must  be 
inferred  from  it  no  less  than  their  existence — in  a  word, 
God  must  be  called  the  cause  of  all  things  in  the  same 
sense  as  he  is  called  the  cause  of  Himself.  This  will  be 
made  still  clearer  by  the  following  corollary.  Corollary. 
Individual  things  are  nothing  but  modifications  of  the 
attributes  of  God,  or  modes  by  which  the  attributes  of 
God  are  expressed  in  a  fixed  and  definite  manner."* 

It  will  be  sufficiently  evident  to  the  reader  that  Spinoza 
has  only  carried  to  its  consistent  issue  the  Cartesian  prin- 
ciple which  Malebranche  had  indeed  enunciated,  but  with- 
out admitting  its  full  bearing,  namely,  that  unless  we 
knew  the  Infinite,  or  God,  we  could  know  nothing  else, 
inasmuch  as  the  human  mind  is  simply  a  modification  of 
the  Divine  Substance.  The  idea  of  this  absolute  unity 
is  involved  in  the  idea  of  every  particular  thing,  and  the 
only  reason  ordinary  men  are  unable  to  discover  it  is 
because  their  ideas  are  confused,  in  short,  because,  owing 
to  the  illusions  of  sense  and  imagination,  they  are  unable 
to  arrive  at  a  clear  and  distinct  idea  of  anything. 

*  Xow  and  always  I  quote  from  the  excellent  translation  of 
Spinoza's  works  by  Mr.  Elwes,  published  in  '  Bohn's  Philosophical 
Library.' 


162  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

Spinoza  insists  on  the  parallellism  between  the  world- 
order  in  Thought  and  the  world-order  in  Extension.  "  The 
order  and  connection  of  ideas"  he  says  (Ethics,  Prop,  vii.), 
"  is  the  same  as  the  order  and  connection  of  things.""  This 
is  as  much  as  to  say  the  One  Substance  may  be  viewed 
either  as  thinking  or  as  extended.  "  Whatsoever  follows 
from  the  infinite  nature  of  God  in  the  world  of  extension 
(forrnaliter),  follows  without  exception  in  the  same  order 
and  connection  from  the  idea  of  God  in  the  world  of 
thought  (^ohjective)."  And  again  :  "  Substance  thinking 
and  substance  extended  are  one  and  the  same  substance, 
comprehended  now  through  one  attribute  and  now 
through  the  other."  "  In  the  same  way  the  mode  of  ex- 
tension and  the  idea  of  that  mode  are  one  and  the  same 
thing,  though  expressed  in  two  ways.  For  instance,  a 
circle  existing  in  nature  and  the  idea  of  a  circle  existing, 
which  is  also  in  God,  are  one  and  the  same  thing  displayed 
through  diiferent  attributes.  Thus  whether  we  consider 
nature  under  the  attribute  of  extension,  or  under  the 
attribute  of  thought,  or  under  any  other  attribute,  we 
shall  find  the  same  order,  and  one  and  the  same  chain  of 
causes — that  is,  the  same  things  following  in  either  case." 
"  I  said  that  God  is  the  cause  of  an  idea — for  instance, 
of  the  idea  of  circle — in  so  far  as  He  is  a  thinking;  thing-. 
and  of  a  circle  in  so  far  as  He  is  an  extended  thing, 
simply  because  the  actual  being  of  the  idea  of  a  circle 
can  only  be  perceived  as  a  proximate  cause  through 
another  mode  of  thinking,  and  that  again,  through  another, 
and  so  on  to  infinity;  so  that  so  long  as  we  consider 
things  as  modes  of  thinking,  we  must  explain  the  order 
of  the  whole  of  nature,  or  the  whole  chain  of  causes, 
through  the  attribute  of  thought  onlj^  And  in  so  far  as 
we  consider  things  as  modes  of  extension,  we  must  explain 
the  order  of  the  whole  of  nature  through  the  attribute  of 
extension  only ;  and  so  on  in  the  case  of  other  attributes. 
Wherefore  of  things  as  they  are  in  themselves,  God  is 
really  the  cause,  inasmuch  as  He  consists  of  infinite 
attributes.  I  cannot  for  the  present  explain  my  meaning 
more  clearly." 

The  impressions  of  the  senses  and  the  mind,  namely, 
that  which  in  the  world  of  thought  corresponds  to  the 


Erocii  I.  A.]  SPINOZA.  1G3 

particular  or  finite  modifications  of  extension,  are  termed 
affectiones.  There  Las  been  much  discussion  among 
students  of  Spinoza  as  to  the  relation  of  the  attributes 
to  the  individual  mind.  In  his  definition  of  attributes, 
Spinoza  says  (1.  Def.  iv.)  :  "By  attribute  I  mean  that 
which  the  intellect  perceives  as  constituting  the  essence 
of  substance."  This  has  been  by  some  interpreted  in  the 
sense  of  Psychological  Idealism,  as  implying  that  the 
attributes  are  simply  the  marks  by  which  the  One  Sub- 
stance is  individualised  in  the  finite  mind,  or  by  which 
it  becomes  aware  of  itself.  According  to  this  view,  the 
attiibutes  are  not  essential  distinctions  in  the  substance 
itself,  but  only  indicate  its  nature  to  the  reflecting  intellect, 
that  is,  they  are  the  form  under  which  the  latter  appre- 
hends it.  On  the  other  hand,  there  are  Spinozists  who 
strenuously  deny  this  phenomenal  acceptation  of  the 
doctrine,  and  maintain  that  the  attributes  represent  a 
noumenal  fact.  For  the  first  of  these  views,  it  may  be 
alleged  that  Spinoza  in  his  definition  (Def.  iv.)  when  he 
refers  to  the  perceiving  intellect,  seems  to  make  an  inten- 
tional deviation  from  Descartes,  who  speaks  of  the  attribute 
simply  as  constituting  the  essence  of  the  substance.  The 
second  view,  on  the  other  hand,  is  supported  by  the  asser- 
tion of  the  infinity  of  attributes.  We  suspect  that  the 
point  was  one  upon  which  Spinoza  was  not  very  clear 
himself;  also  that  here,  as  eLsewhere  in  the  Cartesian 
school,  the  effects  "of  the  reaction  against  scholasticism 
which  was  manifested  in  the  neglect  of  Aristotelian  dis- 
tinctions, is  responsible  for  much  ambiguity,  and  possibly 
some  confusion  of  thought. 

Extension  is  spoken  of  by  Spinoza  as  infinite,  no  less 
than  Thought;  but  the  relation  of  the  unconditioned 
to  the  conditioned  form  of  these  attributes  is  imperfectly 
indicated.  All  limitation  must  be  abstracted  from  the 
attributes  conceived  as  natura  naturans^  and  this  applies 
as  much  to  thought  as  to  extension;  hence,  God  is  no 
more  to  be  conceived  as  will,  which  is  only  a  particular 
limitation  of  thought,  than  He  is  to  be  conceived  as 
body,  which  is  only  a  particular  limitation  of  extension. 
Spinoza  distinctly  repudiates  (Ethics,  Part  II.  Prop,  xliii.) 
any  such  thing  as  an  unconscious  idea ;  he  carefully  warns 

M  2 


164  3I0DERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

us  against  understanding  by  idea  a  mere  prototype  wliicli 
can  never  enter  into  consciousness,  and  demands  that  we 
should  regard  it  as  a  conscious  act  of  thought.  Inasmuch 
as  the  One  Substance  is  the  foundation  of  all  being,  it  is 
the  foundation  of  corporeal  no  less  than  of  mental  pro- 
cesses. Every  such  process  is  conditioned  by  another 
such,  and  that  by  another,  and  so  on  to  infinity.  (See 
quotation,  p.  162,  sujpra.)  Of  course  this  occurs  only  in 
the  same  attribute,  for  we  have  already  seen  that  there 
is  no  passing  over  from  the  one  to  the  other ;  no  more 
from  the  mental  to  the  corporeal,  than  from  the  corporeal 
to  the  mental.  By  Spinoza's  rigid  division  it  is  needless  to 
say  all  idealist  explanations  in  physics,  no  less  than  all 
materialist  explanations  in  psychology,  are  excluded. 

Turning  now  to  natura  naturata,  we  find  the  principles 
of  the  corporeal  w^orld  were,  to  Spinoza,  rest  and  motion. 
All  modifications  of  body  he  attributes  to  the  velocity  and 
direction  of  motion  in  its  parts.  The  so-called  union  of 
body  and  sotil  only  means  that  the  same  thing  is  viewed 
now^  under  one  attribute,  now  under  another.  The  mind 
is  nothing  more  than  the  idea  of  the  body,  but  inasmuch 
as  an  idea  is  only  a  product  of  thought-activity,  the  idea 
corporis  is  a  conscious  act  of  the  mind  with  which  is  bound 
up  the  reflected  knowledge  of  this  act,  that  is,  the  idea  of 
this  idea,  which  is  nothing  other  than  the  idea  mentis. 
Just  as  the  modification  of  extension,  or  body,  of  which 
the  real  or  empirical  world  consists,  is  brought  about  by 
differences  of  rest  and  motion — in  short,  as  an  individual 
body  is  a  determinate  system  of  the  modifications  of  body 
or  extension — so  an  individual  mind  is  a  determinate 
system  of  the  modifications  of  thought,  i.e.  of  ideas.  The 
world  of  eternal  modes,  or  natura  naturata,  roughly 
corresponds  to  the  world  of  Ideas  in  Platonic  systems. 
The  natura  naturata  is,  of  course,  also  to  be  conceived 
under  the  dual  attribute.  It  consists  of  motion  and  rest, 
and  what  Spinoza  terms  the  intellectus  infinitus..  Just  as 
motion  and  rest  contains  the  possibility  of  the  actual 
coq^oreal  world  in  its  entirety,  so  the  intellectus  infitii- 
tus  is  the  complex  of  all  ideas  and  minds,  i.e.  the  possi- 
bility of  the  actual  ideal  world  in  its  entirety.  Just  as 
every  individual  body  is  conditioned  by  motion  and  restj 


Erocii  I.A.]  SPINOZA.  105 

so  is  every  individual  mind  conditioned  by  the  intellectns 
iiijinitus* 

Inasmuch  as  Spinoza  regards  man  merely  as  a  portion 
of  nature,  his  Anthropology  and  Ethics  are  one.  Man's 
bodil}"  slate  is  conditioned  by  the  bodies  which  surround 
him,  his  milieu^  as  it  might  now  be  expressed.  He  is  at 
once  active  and  passive.  His  activity  is  continually 
obstructed  and  affected  by  his  surroundings,  and  his 
whole  career  is  a  continuous  striving  to  realise  himself, 
or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  to  assert  his  own  being, 
against  this  obstruction.  The  consciousness  of  stri^in^ 
is  primarily  appetite  or  desire,  which  leads,  accor(';ing 
as  the  struggle  fails  or  succeeds  in  any  particular  in- 
stance, to  joy  and  sorrow ;  hope  and  fear  being  further 
modifications  of  these  fundamental  emotions  (jpassiones). 
With  the  passions  are  directly  connected  the  conceptions 
of  good  and  evil,  which  can  have  no  meaning  in  any  other 
than  a  human  relation.  The  proposition,  "  this  is  good 
for  me,"  is  perfectly  justified,  but  not  so  the  proposition, 
*'  this  is  good "  (absolutely).  The  presence,  with  the 
emotion  of  joy  or  sorrow,  of  the  idea  of  the  object  causing 
it,  produces  love  or  hatred. 

The  result  of  Spinoza's  Ethics  proper  (contained  in 
the  third  part  of  the  treatise  under  that  name,  the  first 
two  parts  being  purely  metaphysical),  which,  as  we 
before  said,  is  identical  with  his  Anthropology,  is  in 
many  points  similar  to  that  of  his  cuntemporar}^,  Helvetius. 
He  is  a  rigid  necessarian,  and  pure  disinterestedness  he 
regards  as  an  illusion,  since  man  acts  according  to  the 
dictates  of  his  nature,  the  stimulus  to  action  in  men 
being  only  possible  to  be  mortified  or  destroyed  by  a 
stronger  stimulus.  This  of  course  forms  the  foundation 
for  Spinoza's  political  theory.  Spinoza  was  the  first 
consistent  advocate  of  universal  toleration,  although 
he  does  not  recognise  formally  the  "  rights  of  man " 
as  such.  Like  most  political  theorists  of  the  seven- 
teenth century,  all  his  hypotheses  were  based  on  the  as- 

*  Between  tlie  individual  mind,  with  its  manifold  of  reality,  and  the 
pure  undetermined  attribute  of  thought,  stands  the  determination  of 
this  attribute  as  Infinite  Intellect,  i.e.  as  comprehending  under  its 
eternal  modes  the  infinite  complexity  of  the  real  world.     . 


166  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

sumption  of  the  incurable  stupidity  of  the  many ;  but  he  at 
the  same  time  regards  that  state  as  most  secure  in  which 
there  is  the  greatest  amount  of  personal  liberty.  The 
great  truth  which  the  present  century  has  brought  to 
light  of  the  dependence  of  the  political  and  other  forms  of 
society  upon  its  economical  conditions  had  not  then 
dawned,  any  more  than  the  truth  that  the  social  organism 
obeys  certain  definite  laws  of  development  just  as  does 
the  animal  organism. 

Apart  from  this,  however,  perhaps  what  strikes  one 
most  in  reading  Spinoza  is  the  modernness  of  his  style  and 
standpoint  as  compared  with  other  seventeenth-century 
thinkers.  There  are  passages  in  the  "  Tractatus  Theologico- 
politicus,"  as  well  as  in  the  "  Ethics,"  which  might  have  oeen 
written  by  a  modern  scientist.  As  an  instance  of  Spinoza's 
capacity  for  scientific  exposition,  we  quote  a  passage  from 
a  remarkable  letter  of  his  to  Oldenburg.  He  is  endeavour- 
ino-  to  explain  to  Oldenbnrg  the  principle  that  every  part 
of  nature  agrees  with  the  whole,  and  is  associated  with 
all  other  parts  :  "  Let  us  imagine,  with  your  permission,  a 
little  worm,  living  in  the  bluod,  able  to  distinguish  by  sight 
the  particles  of  blood,  lymph,  &c.,  and  to  reflect  on  the 
manner  in  which  each  particle,  on  meeting  with  another 
particle,  either  is  repulsed  or  communicates  a  portion  of 
its  own  motion.  This  little  worm  would  live  in  the 
blood,  in  the  same  way  as  we  live  in  a  part  of  the  universe, 
and  would  consider  each  drop  of  blood,  not  as  a  part,  but 
as  a  w^hole.  He  would  be  unable  to  determine  how  all 
the  parts  are  modified  by  the  general  nature  of  blood,  and 
are  compelled  by  it  to  adapt  themselves,  so  as  to  stand  in 
a  fi.xed  relaiion  to  one  another.  For,  if  we  imagine  that 
there  are  no  causes  external  to  the  blood,  which  could 
communicate  fresh  movements  to  it,  nor  any  space  beyond 
the  blood,  nor  any  bodies  whereto  the  particles  of  blood 
could  communicate  their  motion,  it  is  certain  that  the 
blood  would  always  remain  in  the  same  state,  and  its 
particles  would  undergo  no  modifications,  save  those 
which  may  be  conceived  as  arising  from  the  relations  of 
motion  existing  between  the  lymph,  the  chyle,  &c.  Tho 
blood  would  then  always  have  to  be  considered  as  a  whole, 
not  a  part.     But,  as  there  exist,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  very 


!,ErocHjX]  LEIBNITZ.  167 

many  causes,  which  modify,  in  a  given  manner,  the  nature 
of  the  blood,  and  are,  in  tuin,  modified  thereby,  it  follows 
that  other  motions  and  other  relations  arise  in  the 
blood,  springing  not  from  the  mutual  relations  of  its 
parts  only,  but  from  the  mutual  relations  between  the 
blood  as  a  whole  and  external  causes.  Thus  the  blood 
comes  to  be  regarded  as  a  part,  not  as  a  whole.  So  much 
for  the  whole  and  the  part." 

In  many  points  Spinoza  anticipates  Kant,  but  his  funda- 
mental conceiDtion  is  still  abstract.  The  Unica  Substantia 
is,  after  all,  at  bottom,  the  Being-in-general  of  the  Carte- 
sians and  of  Malebranche.  His  system  is  an  ontology, 
and  an  ontology,  too,  in  which  all  traces  of  "  theory  of 
knowledge,"  as  such,  are  absent. 

Spinozism  found  an  immediate  success  in  Holland. 
Numerous  works  appeared,  some  containing  views  ob- 
viously drawn  from  the  Ethics,  others  attacking  those 
views.  About  the  close  of  the  seventeenth  century,  it 
appears  to  have  gained  some  ground  in  France. 

Spinoza's  is  the  only  pre-Kantian  system  which  has 
been  revived  in  modern  times.  In  fact,  the  interest  in 
Spinoza  dates  mostly  from  Goethe  and  Schleiermacher. 
The  works  which  have  been  published  during  the  last 
half-century,  dealing  with  the  Dutch  thinker,  would  fill  a 
library.  There  are  not  wanting,  at  the  present  day,  men 
of  eminence  who  declare  that  in  him  is  contained  the 
fulness  of  modern  science  manifested.  With  Spinoza 
closes  the  main  line  of  Cartesian  development.  We  now 
proceed  to  consider  a  subsidiary  branch  springing  from 
the  same  stem. 

Among  recent  English  works  treating  of  Spinoza  and  his  philo- 
sophy may  be  mentioned,  Willis's  '  Spinoza,  his  Life,  Letters  and 
Ethics,'  Frederick  Pollock's  '  Life  and  Works  of  Spinoza,'  Martine.iu's 
'  Spinoza,'  &c.,  &c.  The  German  works  ou  the  subject  are  numerous 
and  well-known. 

LEIBNITZ. 

Gottfried  Wilhelm  Leibnitz  was  bom,  1646,  at  Leipsic, 
and  was  educated  in  the  university  of  that  town.  An 
omnivorous   reader,   he    early   attained   considerable    ac- 


168  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. a. 

quaintance  witli  the  history  of  philosophy.  In  Jena, 
where  he  subsequently  studied,  he  read  Hobbes  and  Locke, 
in  addition  to  Kepler,  Galilei,  and  other  scientific  writers. 
His  journey  to  Paris,  though  it  failed  in  its  immediate 
purpose  of  inducing  Louis  XIV.  to  undertake  an  Egyptian 
expedition,  had  as  its  result  the  mathematical  education 
of  Leibnitz.  It  was  in  Paris,  in  1676,  that  he  discovered 
the  diiferential  calculus.  Here,  also,  he  first  began 
seriously  to  study  Descartes  and  Spinoza.  In  1684, 
Leibnitz  removed  to  Berlin,  and  shortly  after  undertook 
a  lengthened  archaeological  expedition  to  Italy.  On  his 
return  to  Berlin,  he  became  president  of  the  newly  con- 
stituted Prussian  Academy,  as  well  as  the  occupant  of  a 
diplomatic  post.  With  the  death  of  the  Queen  of  Prussia 
in  1711,  his  connection  with  Berlin  ceased.  He  died  in 
Vienna,  in  1716,  loaded  with  honours.  The  latter  part  of 
his  life  is  said  to  have  been  embittered  by  his  quarrels 
with  the  Newtonians. 

Leibnitz's  Doctrines. 

In  philosophy  Leibnitz  stands  in  one  sense  at  the 
opposite  pole  to  Spinoza.  JTa  i«  oLiAf  r^^pxesentatiY^of 
wjmt.  IS  coTnTnorjIy  known  as  Pluralism  in  metaphysic,_ie. 
hft  rp.tya.frla  iyn]pnVlnf)f.;.n^  as  an  ultiiuate  and  irreducijile 
fact.  The  result  of  Leibnitz's  scientific  studies  had  led 
him  early  to  accept  the  atomistic  theory  of  the  ultimate 
constitution  of  matter.  This  atomism  he  carried  into 
the  sphere  of  metaphysic.  To  Leibnitz,  substance  was 
mfinitely_jriany.  The  infinitely'^umerous  eternal^  and 
siniple  substan(?es,  unities,  or  forces,  as  they  may  perhaps 
with  equal  right  be  termed,  Leibnitz  designates  monads, 
a  word  originally  employed  by  Bruno.  The  inonads  being 
simple,  could  only  come  into  being  by  creation,  or  cease 
from  being  by  annihilation,  and  besides  them  nothing 
exists.  Although  destitute  of  parts,  extension,  figure, 
or  divisibility,  they  must,  nevertheless,  have  qualities, 
"  otherwise,"  says  Leibnitz,  "  they  would  not  even  be 
entities ;  and  if  simple  substances  did  not  difi'er  in  their 
qualities,  there  would  be  no  means  by  which  we  could 
become  aware  of  the  changes  of  things,  since  all  that  is  in 
compound  bodies  is  derived  from  simple  ingredients ;  and 


Epoch  I. a.]  LEIBNITZ.  169 

moiiads,  being  without  qualities,  would  be  indistinguishable 
one  from  another,  seeing  also  that  they  did  not  differ  in 
quantity."  Every  monad  must  differ  from  every  other, 
for  Leibnitz  postulates  the  axiom  that  "  there  gire  never 
Uvo  beinfjj-s  in  nature  perfectly  alike^  and  in  whicE"  it  J 
impossible  to  find,,  an  internal  diiierence,  or  one  founde 
on  intrinsic  determination." 

~liut  the  metaphysical  monads  of  Leibnitz  differ  from 
the  physical  atoms  of  Demokritos,  in  that  they  are  de- 
termined by  an  internal  principle  of  change,  and  are 
uninfluenced  by  anything  external  to  themselves.  "  But 
besides  the  principle  of  change,"  proceeds  Leibnitz, 
"  there  must  also  be  a  detail  of  changes,  embracing,  so 
to  speak,  the  specification  and  the  variety  of  simple 
substances.  This  detail  must  involve  multitude  in 
litiity  or  in  simplicity,  for  as  all  natural  changes 
proceed  by  degrees,  something  changes  and  something 
remains,  and  consequently,  there  must  be  in  the  simple  sub- 
stance a  plurality  of  affections  or  relations,  although  there 
are  no  parts."  (Monadologie,  12,  13.)  The  section  which 
follows  is  interesting  as  characteristic  of  Leibnitz's  mode 
of  thought,  and  as  showing  the  first  distinct  enunciation 
of  a  doctrine  which  has  played  a  not  unimportant  part  in 
subsequent  speculation — that  of  the  uncousciouj  per- 
ception or  idea.  "  This  shifting  state,  which  involves  and 
represents  multitude  in  unity,  or  in  the  simple  substance, 
is  nothing  else  than  what  we  call  perception,  which  must 
be  carefully  distinguished  from  apj^erception,  or  conscious- 
ness, as  will  appear  in  the  sequel.  Here  it  is  that  the 
.jJartesians  have  specially  failed,  making  no  account  of 
those"per^ptions~ of ^^Heb-3^'5HJ  nut  Grmsm'm^jg^  TX^ 
iMs-^EsithaS  led  them  to  suppose  that  spirits  are  the  only 
monads,  and  that  there  are  no  souls  of  brutes  or  other 
Entelechies.  It  is  owing  to  this  that  they  have  vulgarly 
confounded  protracted  torpor  with  actual  death,  and  have 
fallen  in  with  the  scholastic  prejudice,  which  postulates 
souls  entirely  separate.  Hence,  also,  ill-affected  minds 
have  been  confirmed  in  the  opinion  that  the  soul  is 
mortal." 

Leibnitz,  of  course,  strenuously  opposes  all  mechanical 
explanations  of  perception,     "If  we  imagine  a  machine 


170  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

SO  constructed,"  he  says,  "as  to  produce  thought, 
sensation,  perception,  we  may  conceive  it  magnified 
— the  same  proportions  being  preserved — to  such  an 
extent  that  one  might  enter  it  like  a  mill.  This 
being  supposed,  we  should  find  in  it,  on  each  inspection, 
only  pieces  which  impel  each  other,  but  nothing  which 
can  explain  perception.  It  is  in  the  simple  substance, 
therefore — not  in  the  compound,  or  in  machinery — that 
we  must  look  for  that  phenomenon ;  and  in  the  simple 
substance  we  find  nothing  else — nothing,  that  is,  but 
perceptions  and  their  changes.  Therein  also,  and  therein 
only,  consist  all  the  internal  acts  of  simple  substances." 
Leibnitz  recognises  a  progre-ssion  or  hierarchy  among  the 
monads,  from  the  simj3le  monad  which  is  purely  unconscious 
or  confused,,  to  the  monad  which  has  attained  to  self- 
consciousness  or  clearness.  .  The  term  soul  he  woujd 
reserve  Tur  the  latter.  When  we  are  in  a  profound  and 
dreamless  sleep,  or  in  a  swoon,  "  the  soul  does  not  differ 
sensibly  from  the  simple  monad ;  bur'smc'e^thts^  state^iS 
not  permanent,  and  since' the  soul  delivers  herself  from  it, 
she  is  something  more."  In  much  of  this  we  see  Leibnitz 
as  a  true  successor  of  Descartes  ;  the  Cartesian  distinction 
between  confused  and  clear  perception  being  made  nou- 
menal.  The  impossibility  of  the  entire  absence  of 
perception  in  the  thinking  subject  here  receives  a  new 
application,  in  so  far  as  perception  is  formally  distinguished 
from  consciousness.  If  there  were  no  distinction  in  our 
perceptions,  we  should  continue  for  ever  in  a  state  of 
stupor :  "  and  this,"  adds  Leibnitz,  "  is  the  condition  of 
the  naked  monad."  "  Where  there  is  a  great  number  of 
minute  perceptions,  but  where  nothing  is  distinct,  one  is 
stunned,  as  when  we  turn  round  and  round  in  continual 
succession  in  the  same  direction,  whence  arises  a  vertigo 
which  may  cause  us  to  faint,  and  which  prevents  us  from 
distinguishing  anything." 

Memory,  accordino;  to  Leibnitz,  gives  to  the  SQula 
gonsfif^nt,ivft"ant,iori,  hut  m"u^t  "h*^  fliKtiiio-nishfMl  fr^pi  reason . 
Leibnitz  is  prepared  to  recognise  a  large  measure  oT'Tfuth. 
in  the  English  Empiricist  school.  ^1^^2^3^  ^"^  ^'^if"* 
consecutiveness  of  perce^^t^'"^";  ^'«  «hared  in  common-bv 
^^u.  ^n^  animals.      It    is   th^  RnipTitijfic  reason  which 


Eiocir  I. A.]  LEIBNITZ.  171 

distin<yiiishcs  maa,     Tho  distinction   between 


empirical  knowledge  derived  from  the  former  source,  and 
that  derived  from  the  latter,  is  illustrated  by  the  following 
familiar  instance  :  when  we  expect  the  sun  to  rise  to- 
morrow, we  judge  so  empirically,  because  it  has  always 
done  so  hitherto ;  but  the  astronomer  makes  the  same 
judgment  by  an  act  of  reason.  In  the  same  way  the 
difference  between  a  quack  and  a  physician  consists  in  the 
fact  that  the  one  has  only  practice,  or  knowledge  picked 
up  in  a  casual  way  to  rely  upon,  while  the  other  derives 
his  knowledge  from  scientific  theory.  The  celebrated 
proposition  directed  by  Leibnitz  against  Locke,  "  nihil  est 
in  intellectu  quod  non  prius  in  sensu  fuerit,  nisi  ipse  in- 
teUectus,''  expresses  in  a  sentence  this  cardinal  distinction 
between  empirical  and  necessary  truth. 

nnho_flr>jj2f^^b^^^7  is  thft  p_n]3reme  mo'pg.d  nr  primitive 
nrnj^yTthe  _simple  original  substance  ofwhich^aiCSifi, 
nrftalgdoT]_j^i^^d— monadjsL-^  "the^p  r  orli  i  cts .  and  which 
are"geherated,  "  so  to  speak,  by  continual  fulgurations  "oT 
tEe  divimty  from  moment  to  moment,  bounded  by  the 
receptations  of  the  creature  of  whose  existence  limitation 
is  an  essential  condition."  Like  the  God  of  the  schoolman, 
he  is  actus  purus,  to  which  tho  created  monads  approach  in 
varying  degrees,  "according  to  the  measure  of  their 
perfection."  The  creatftd  rponindn  rnn  ^nly  riint  upnn  on^ 
another  through  the  medii]m  nf  f,he  divine  monad.  It  is 
only  through  it  that  one  can  be  dependent  upon  the  other. 
Leibnitz  bases  his  optimism  on  the  principle  of  sufficient 
reason.  The  principle  of  suffi,cicnt  reason  declares  thait 
no  fact  canBe*^  real,  or  existent,  no  statement  true,  unless 
there  be  a  sufficient  reason  whyiiTis  thns^  aj|fl_T)nf.  others 
wise,  altEgu.a:h  these  x^sons  very  often  cannot  be  known"^ 
to  us."  'rhis  principle  leads  us  to  infer  that  since  out  of 
the  infinite  number  of  possible  worlds,  this  one  has  been 
created  by  the  Divine  mind,  it  must  contain  within  it  the 
greatest  possible  measure  of  perfection.  "  And  this  con- 
nection, or  this  accommodation  of  all  created  things  to 
each,  and  of  each  to  all,  implies  in  each  simple  substance 
relations  which  express  all  the  rest.  Each,  accordingly, 
is  a  living  and  perpetual  mirror  of  the  universe.  And  as 
the  same  city  viewed  from  different  sides  appears  quite 


172  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I. a. 

different,  and  is  perspectively  multiplied,  so,  in  the  infinite 
multitude  of  simple  substances,  there  are  given,  as  it 
were,  so  many  different  worlds  which  yet  are  only  per- 
spectives of  a  single  one,  according  to  the  different  points 
of  view  of  each  monad.  And  this  is  the  way  to  obtain 
the  greatest  possible  variety  with  the  greatest  possible 
order :  that  is  to  say,  the  way  to  obtain  the  greatest 
possible  perfection."  Every  monad  contains  the  infinity 
of  being  in  itself.  It  would  lose  nothing  if  all  other 
monads  were  destroyed,  nor  gain  anything  if  they  could 
act  upon  it.  The  monad  is  a  self-sufficient  microcosm, 
and  an  omniscient  eye  might  see  in  its  present  state  the 
whole  past  and  future  of  the  universe.  "  But  each  soul 
can  read  in  itself  only  that  which  is  distinctly  represented 
in  it.  It  cannot  unfold  its  laws  at  ouce,  for  they  leach 
into  the  infinite."  Every  organic  body  is  a  species  of 
*'  divine  machine,"  surpassing  all  human  mechanisms  by  the 
infinite  complexity  of  its  relations.  Each  portion  of  matter 
expresses  the  universe ;  that  is,  each  portion  of  matter 
has  its  special  formation  energj^  or  soul.  "  Every  particle  of 
matter,"  say  Leibnitz,  "  may  be  conceived  as  a  garden  full 
of  plants,  or  as  a  pond  full  of  fishes.  But  each  branch  of 
each  plant,  each  member  of  each  animal,  each  drop  of  their 
humours,  is  in  its  turn  another  such  garden  or  pond.' 
Death,  chaos,  and  barrenness,  exist  only  in  appearance, 
owing  to  the  imperfection  of  our  point  of  view.  It  must 
not  be  supposed,  however,  that  each  entelechy,  force,  or 
soul,  has  a  special  portion  of  matter  for  ever  united  with 
it ;  for  all  bodies  are  in  a  perpetual  flux,  like  rivers,  their 
particles  for  ever  coming  and  going.  "  That  which  we 
call  generation  is  development  and  accretion,  and  that, 
which  we  call  death  is  envelopment  and  diminution." 
There  is  no  destruction  either  of  the  soul  or  the  body, 
strictly  speaking.  They  each  follow  their  proper  laws, 
and  coincide  by  virtue  of  the  "  pre-established  harmony," 
which  exists  between  all  substances  as  representations  of 
one  and  the  same  universe.  Leibnitz  maintains  that  had 
Descartes  known  the  laws  of  motion,  he  would  have  been 
led  to  discover  this  principle  of  the  "pre-established 
harmony,"  by  which,  to  quote  his  words,  "  bodies  act  as 
if  there  were  no  souls,  and  souls  act  as  if  there  v\ere: 


Erocii  I.A.]  LEIBNITZ.  173 

no  bodies ;  and  j^et  both  act  as  if  the  one  influenced  the 
other." 

The  foregoing  exposition  we  have  taken  almost  verbatim 
from  the  summary  of  his  system,  written  by  Leibnitz  in 
1714,  for  Prince  Eugene  of  Savoy,  and  published  after  his 
death  as  the  "  Monadology."  The  inconsistency  and 
mutual  incompatibility  of  several  of  the  main  joositions 
taken  up  are  apparent  at  a  glance.  Leibnitz  is  emphatic 
in  declaring  that  the  monads  have  "  no  windows,"  while 
at  the  same  time  postulating  a  direct  relation  between 
them  and  the  supreme  monad,  and  an  indirect  relation 
with  one  another.  It  is  difficult  to  see,  on  Leibnitzian 
principles,  how  psychological  idealism  is  to  be  avoided; 
The  self-centred  microcosm  ex  hypotliesi  knows  only  its 
own  universe.  In  this  it  is  absolutely  shut  up.  How 
then  has  it  any  right  to  pronounce  on  the  absolute  nature 
of  things  outside  this  universe?  It  may  be  quite  true 
that  other  self-centred  monads  may  exist  as  the  centres  of 
different  worlds,  but  of  them  it  cannot  possibly  know 
anything.  Those  who  postulate  a  plurality  of  ultimate 
world- principles  can  never  logically  answer  the  questions 
raised  by  "theory  of  knowledge."  Leibnitz  is  involved  in 
additional  difficulties  by  his  theism,  and  above  all,  by  his 
attempts  to  render  his  system  compatible  with  theological 
orthodoxy.  A  hierarchy  of  self-centered  and  essentially 
independent  beings,  extending  from  the  lowest  sentiency 
to  the  highest  consciousness,  may  be  a  pretty  and  sym- 
metrical conception,  but  will  certainly  not  bear  the  test 
of  criticism,  as  an  explanation  of  the  universe. 

But  Leibnitz,  who  after  all  was  more  of  a  litterateur 
than  a  philosopher,  gives  us,  nevertheless,  many  acute 
suggestions  and  able  pieces  of  analysis  in  his  writings. 
His  individualist  Pluralism  he  was  fond  of  placing  in 
opposition  to  Spinoza's  Monism,  when  charged  with  the 
latter  by  thinkers  too  logical  to  conceive  the  possibility  of 
a  serious  thinker  treating  individuation  as  an  ultimate 
metaphysical  fact. 

Leibnitz,  of  course,  admits  freedom  of  the  will,  but  his 
freedom  is  neither  absolute  indiflference,  nor  is  it  determi- 
nation without  motive.  It  is  a  free  choice  of  one  line  of 
conduct  rather  than  another  from  among  two  or  more 


174  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

that  are,  physically  speaking,  equally  possible.  God  alone 
is  absolutely  free.  Human  freedom  merely  means  that 
the  determination  of  the  will  is  contingent  upon  the 
character.  In  this  sense,  "  the  understanding  may  deter- 
mine the  will  according  to  the  prevalence  of  perceptions 
and  reasons  of  one  kind  which,  since  it  is  certain  and 
infallible,  may  incline  without  necessitating  it  "  (Nouveaux 
Essais,  XXI.).  In  a  certain  sense,  a  ball  might  be  said  to  be 
free  after  it  has  been  struck  by  a  racquet,  in  so  far  as  its 
movement  is  not  hindered.  In  another  sense,  the  motion 
of  the  ball  is  contingent,  in  other  words,  not  free. 

Leibnitz  warns  the  student  against  the  misuse  of  the 
Cartesian  principle  of  "  clearness  and  distinctness "  in 
idea,  as  a  test  of  truth.  Very  often  that  appears  to  us 
clear  and  distinct,  which  is  really  dark  and  confused. 
The  test  of  clearness  and  distinctness  is  only  applicable 
when  it  is  the  result  of  exact  observation  and  faultless 
deduction.  As  we  have  seen,  in  one  sense  nothing  is  clear 
and  distinct ;  for  example,  our  perception  of  matter  is  in 
its  nature  confused :  matter  which  is  composed  of  an 
infinity  of  unextended  substances,  to  our  perception 
appears  as  a  continuously  extended  whole. 

Leibnitzianism  is  in  every  sense  the  logical  antithesis  of 
Spinozism.  To  Spinoza  there  existed  naught  but  the  one 
substance  and  its  modes ;  to  Leibnitz  existence  comprised 
an  infinity  of  monads  and  their  perceptions.  To  Spinoza, 
extension  is  an  ultimate  fact,  co-relative  with  thought ;  to 
Leibnitz  it  is  an  illusion  due  to  confused  apprehension. 
To  Spinoza,  all  teleological  explanations  are  to  be  rigidly 
excluded  in  philosophy  ;  to  Leibnitz,  they  form  an  integral 
part  of  its  method.  To  Spinoza,  philosophy  had  no  part 
nor  lot  with  theology ;  to  Leibnitz,  the  justification  of 
theology  is  its  end  and  aim.  Leibnitz  was  essentially  an 
eclectic  ;  an  eclectic  in  religion  (he  had  sought,  as  one  of 
the  great  objects  of  his  life,  to  find  a  modus  vivendi  between 
the  Catholic  and  Protestant  churches)  ;  an  eclectic  in  philo- 
sophy, an  eclectic  in  science,  and  last  of  all,  an  eclectic  in 
his  attempts  to  reconcile  philosophy  and  theology. 

The  somewhat  flashy  system  of  Leibnitz,  as  was  natu- 
ral, made  an  immediate  and  widely  extended  imj^restiun 


Epoch  I.a.]  I  LEIBNITZ.  175 

on  the  culture  of  Europe.  It  almost  entirely  su]-»erseded 
Cartesianism  in  the  university  and  in  the  salon,  and 
indeed  was  the  dominant  academical  philosophy  of  the 
Continent  until  the  time  of  Kant,  if  not  in  its  original 
form,  in  one  but  slightly  modified. 

We  pass  over  intermediate  writers,  and  come  to  Christian 
Wolff,  the  first  follower  of  Leibnitz  who  erected  an  inde- 
pendent system  on  the  principles  of  the  master.  Wolff 
was  born  in  1679  at  Breslau,  and  became,  in  1706,  professor 
of  mathematics  in  Halle.  He  subsequently  entered  upon 
a  professorship  at  Marburg,  but  owing  to  alleged  heretical 
tendencies  in  his  doctrines  he  was  recalled,  and  retired 
again  to  Halle,  devoting  himself  mainly  to  literary  work 
till  his  death,  on  the  9th  April,  1754.  Wolff  is  noteworthy 
as  being  the  first  academical  thinker  who  wrote  in  German. 
He  was  the  author  of  a  large  number  of  works  dealing 
with  every  department  of  philosoph}'.  He  attempted 
to  combine  Leibnitzianism  with  the  older  Aristotelian 
doctrines  of  the  schools.  The  pre-established  harmony  he 
regards  simply  as  an  admissible  hypothesis.  He  also 
denies  the  unconscious  perception  of  Leibnitz,  that  is,  he 
refuses  to  admit  perception  in  any  monads  below  the  rank 
of  the  Leibnitzian  soul.  On  the  other  hand,  he  adheres  to 
the  optimism  of  his  master  no  less  than  to  his  doctrine  of 
the  will.  His  division  of  philosophy  into  Ontology,  or  the 
doctrine  of  being  in  general ;  Rational  Psychology,  or  the 
doctrine  of  the  soul  as  unextended  and  simple  substance ; 
Cosmology,  or  the  doctrine  of  the  physical  universe ;  and 
Eational  Theology,  or  the  doctrine  of  the  existence  and 
attributes  of  God,  is  interesting  and  noteworthy  in  its 
relation  to  the  "  critique  "  of  Kant,  as  we  shall  presently 
see.  Practical  philosophy  (an  expression  since  much  used 
in  Germany,  of  which  apparently  he  was  the  originator)  he 
divides  into  Ethics,  Economics,  and  Politics  (the  old 
Aristotelian  division).  Wolff  bases  his  "  practical  philo- 
sophy "  on  the  idea  of  perception,  which  is  the  law  of  our 
rational  nature. 

Wolff  left  an  extensive  school  behind  him,  the  most 
noteworthy  name  of  which  is  that  of  Alexander  Gottlieb 
Baumgarten  (born,  1714,  in  Berlin,  died,  1762,  in  Frank- 
fort).    Baumgarten  is  chiefly  remarkable  for  two  things; 


176  MODERN    PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.a. 

firstly  for  having  attempted  to  construct  a  philosophy  of 
{esthetics,  and  secondly  for  having  been  the  thinker  who 
probably  had  most  share  in  the  earlier  philosophical 
education  of  Immanuel  Kant.  Baumgarten  was  Kant's 
type  of  the  dogmatic  metaphysician,  as  often  appears  in 
his  works.  The  only  other  member  of  the  school  worthy 
of  notice,  and  for  the  same  reason,  is  Christian  August 
Ceusius  (born,  1712,  died,  1776,  professor  of  philosophy  at 
Leipsic).  He  also  had  an  influence  on  the  philosophical 
education  of  Kant,  and  is  often  referred  to  by  him. 


(    177    ) 

MODERN  PHILOSOPHY. 

FIRST  EPOCH,  B. 
THE  EMPIKICAL  SCEPTICAL  SCHOOLS. 

BACON. 

We  have  now  traced  the  course  of  the  dogmatic  schools 
of  the  Continent  from  the  rehabilitation  of  philosophy, 
after  the  fall  of  scholasticism  had  been  succeeded  by  the 
brilliant  literary  revivals  of  ancient  systems,  followed 
by  the  fantastic  physical  speculations  of  the  sixteenth 
century ;  and  after  these  in  their  turn  had  collapsed — in 
other  words,  from  the  period  of  Descartes.  We  liave 
followed  this  development  to  the  middle  of  the  eighteenth 
century,  that  is,  to  the  time  of  Immanuel  Kant.  Here  we 
must  retrace  our  steps  to  the  period  at  which  we  started 
in  the  survej"  just  concluded,  i.e.  to  the  beginning  of  the 
seventeenth  century,  for  the  purpose  of  following  the 
contemporaneous,  though  essentially  distinct  Empiricist 
movement  in  the  British  Islands. 

The  first  name  we  meet  with  in  this  Empiricist  move- 
ment is  that  of  Francis  Bacon,  Lord  Verulam.  "By 
eliminating  the  theosophic  character  which  Natural 
Philosophy  had  acquired  during  the  transitional  period," 
says  Ueberweg  (vol.  iii.  p.  35),  "  by  the  limitation  of  its 
method  to  experiences  and  induction,  and  by  raising  the 
fundamental  characteristics  of  this  method  to  a  philo- 
sophical dignity  free  from  the  narrowness  attaching  to 
any  special  circle  of  physical  research,  Bacon  of  Verulam 
(1561-1626)  is  the  founder,  not  indeed  of  the  empirical 
method  in  natural  science,  but  of  the  empiricist  line  of 
development  in  modern  philosophy."  The  notion  of 
reorganising  human  knowledge  on  a  new  basis  was,  it 
is  said,  a  favourite  dream  of  Bacon,  even  in  his  boyhood. 
Like  his  younger  contemporary,  Descartes,  he  had  been 
early  disgusted  with  the  metaphysic  of  the  schools.  The 
growing  enthusiasm  for  physical  science  had  seized  him 

N 


178  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

also  ;  but,  unlike  the  Frenchnian,  lie  did  not  dream  of 
bringing  knowledge  back  to  the  primitive  cogito  by  any 
drastic  scepticism. 

In  his  '111  Stan  ration  of  the  Sciences,'  Bacon  makes 
a  survey  of  knowledge,  as  it  then  existed,  as  a  pre- 
limiuary  to  the  work  of  reform.  It  falls  under  three 
heads,  Memory,  Imagination,  and  Eeason.  In  this  portion 
of  his  great  work,  Bacon  points  out  what  he  conceived  as 
the  fundamental  sources  of  error  in  the  human  mind,  to 
which  he  gives  the  name  of  Idols  in  the  Greek  sense  of 
the  word  (ctSwAov).  This,  perhaps  the  most  interesting 
and  important  part  of  the  work  in  question,  is  succeeded 
by  a  dissertation  on  the  three  branches  of  human  science 
which  fall  respectively  under  the  above  heads,  viz.. 
History,  Poetry,  and  Philosophy.  Philosophy,  according 
to  Bacon,  concerns  itself  with  God,  Man,  and  Nature.  The 
first  department,  that  of  natural  theology,  consists  of  the 
attempt  to  show  that  the  series  of  physical  causes  implies 
a  first  cause  and  a  Providence.  On  the  positive  nature  and 
attributes  of  God,  natural  or  philosophical  theology  has 
nothing  to  say.  Siuiilarly,  in  the  second  department, 
that  which  has  Man  for  its  object,  it  is  not  the  immaterial 
soul  of  man  which  is  immediately  breathed  into  him  by 
the  Deity  that  jDhilosophy  deals  with,  but  the  animal  soul, 
which  is  of  a  thinner,  finer,  corporeal  nature  than  the 
body,  but  not  immaterial.* 

Natural  philosophy,  the  third  department,  is  divided 
into  two  sections,  speculative  and  operative.  Speculative 
natural  philosophy  is  again  divided  into  physics  and 
metaphysics;  the  first  in  so  far  as  it  is  concerned  with 
proximate  causes,  the  second  in  so  far  as  it  deals  with 
ends.  Operative  natural  philosophy  is  divided  •  into 
two  corresponding  sections,  as  applied  physic  it  is 
termed  mechanic,— as  applied  metaphysic,  natural  magic. 
The  fundamental  conceptions  and  axioms  which  lie 
at  the  root  of  all'  philosophy,  such  as  those  of  being 
and  non-being,  similarity  and  diversity,  &c.,  or  such 
an  axiom  as  that  two  things  that  are  equal  to  the  same' 
thing  are  equal  to  one  another,  form  the  subject-matter  of 

*  The  coincidence  of  this  with  the  doctrine  of  Paracelsus  is  curious. 


ErocTi  I.B.]  BACON.  179 

what  B<acon  terms  plnJosopMa  prima  or  scientia  universalis. 
Mathematics  is  merely  the  auxiliary  science  of  physics. 
Anthropology,  or  the  science  of  Man,  refers  partly  to  the 
human  body  and  partly  to  the  soul,  in  the  sense  above 
indicated.  Bacon  ascribes  all  the  elements  of  bodies  to 
perception,  which  he  explains  mechanically  as  the  result 
of  attraction  and  repulsion.  Like  Leibnitz  at  a  later  date, 
he  distinguishes  between  .mere  perceptions,  and  feelings 
accompanied  by  consciousness,  although  perhaps  not  so 
clearly.  Logic  and  ethics,  no  less  than  politics,  fall  to  be 
dealt  with  in  this  department.  It  is  in  the  portion  of  the 
*'  Novum  Organum  "  dealing  with  method,  in  which  the  idols 
of  the  mind  are  treated  of,  that  the  doctrines  are  to  be 
found  to  which  the  subsequent  philosophic  development 
may  be  most  directly  traced.  Bacon  discovers  in  the 
natural  constitution  of  the  human  mind  a  tendency 
towards  a  deceptive  anthropomorphism,  as  for  instance,  to 
the  substitution  of  final  causes  for  proximate  or  efficient 
causes  in  physic,  fallacies  occasioned  by  which  are  termed 
by  him  Idola  Tribus.  He  finds  also  many  fallacies 
attributable  to  some  special  bias  of  the  individual,  which 
he  terms  Idola  Specus ;  or  again,  others  occasioned  by  the 
mis-use  of  language;  yet  others,  which  spring  from  tradi- 
tional prejudice ;  the  latter  being  styled  respectively 
Idola  Fori  and  Idola  Theatri.  The  mind  has  to  free  itself 
as  far  as  may  be  from  these  infirmities  before  it  is  in  a 
pos\,tion  to  arrive  at  truth.  "We  mUvst,"  says  Bacon, 
"neither  draw  everything  from  ourselves,  as  the  spider 
its  threads,  nor  merely  gather  together  like  the  ants, 
but  gather  together  and  work  up  as  the  bees  their 
honey."  Induction,  as  taught  by  Aristotle  and  the 
schoolmen,  the  so-called  inductio  per  enumerationem  sim- 
plicem,  he  condemns,  since  it  fails  in  this  latter  point, 
namely,  the  subjective  working-up,  by  which  Bacon  means 
the  methodical  and  systematic  reduction  of  the  individual 
instance  under  the  general  rule.  Negative  instances  are 
to  be  taken  account  of  as  much  as  positive,  as  well  as 
differences  of  degree.  The  reduction  is  to  be  undertaken 
with  the  greatest  care,  not  by  springing  at  once  fi^om  the 
singular  to  the  universal,  but  by  proceeding  step  by  step 
through  all  the  intermediate  stages. 

N  2 


180  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY  [Epoch  Lb. 


HOBBES. 

The  next  English  thinker  we  have  to  notice  is  Thomas 
HoBBEs,  the  contemporary  and  friend  of  Bacon.  Hobbes 
was  born  at  Malmesbury  in  1588,  and  as  a  young  man 
became  tutor  in  the  house  of  the  Duke  of  Devonshire. 
Subsequently,  after  a  journey  through  France  and  Italy, 
he  studied  Mathematics  and  Natural  Science  in  Paris,  and 
became  as  enthusiastic  as  his  nature  allowed  in  the  rising 
physical  science,  as  represented  by  Kepler,  Copernicus, 
Galilei,  and  Harvey.  He  produced  a  number  of  works, 
the  most  famous  being  his  treatise  "  On  Human  Nature," 
and  the  celebrated  "  Leviathan ;  or  the  Matter,  Form, 
and  Authoritj^  of  Government."     Hobbes  died  in  1679. 

Hobbes_  defines  philosophy  as  the  cognition^  of  effects  or 
phenomena  from  their  causes,,^nd  of  the  cau^esTFom  th^ 
observed  effects,  by  means  of  correct  deduction.  Its  object 
is  practical,  namely,  that  we  may  foresee  effeiitSj  and 
thereby  make  use  of  them  in  life.  Hobbes  shares  Bacon's 
mecEahical  mode  of  regarding  things,  which  he  in  many 
respects  exaggerates.  Jle  may  justly  ^^  reg^'^^^d  ^s  thp, 
father^  of  British  psychology.  Without  him  fliere  could 
have  been" no  Locke.  ^A  distinct  stand  is  taken  on 
experience  and  observation  as  the  sole  source  of  know- 
ledge. There  is  no  metaphysical  problem  any  more  than 
one  as  to  the  constitution  of  our  knowledge.  "  Concerping 
the  thoughts  of  Man,"  says  he  (Leviathan,  Chap,  i.),  "  I 
will  consider  them  first  singly,  and  afterwards  in  a  train 
of  dependence  upon  one  another.  Singly,  they  are  every- 
one a  representation  or  appearance  of  some  quality  or  other 
accident  of  a  boily  without  us,  which  is  commonly  called 
an  object,  which  object  worketh  on  the  eyes,  ears,  and  other 
parts  of  a  man's  body ;  and,  by  a  diversity  of  working, 
produces  diversity  of  appearances.  The  original  of  them  all 
is  that  which  we  call  sense.  There  is  no  conception  in  a 
man's  mind  which  hath  not  at  first,  totally  or  by  part, 
been  begotten  upon  the  organs  of  sense.  The  rest  are 
derived  from  that  original." 

In  Hobbes  we  have  the  first  distinct  expression  of  the 
English  empiricist  doctrine — the  doctrine  which  has  main- 


Epoch  I.e.]  HOBBES.  181 

tallied  its  ground  in  this  country  up  to  the  present  time. 
Philosophy  in  the  Englifrh  school,  of  which  Hobbes  is  the 
earliest  direct  representative,  is  reduced  in  its  main  issue 
to  a  mere  question  of  psychology.  Is  the  mind  a  tabula 
rasa  receiving  its  knowledge  ready-made  from  an  exter- 
nal source  ?  or  does  it  possess  innate  ideas  by  which  it 
is  enabled  to  form  judgments  of  a  higher  validity  than 
those  which  can  be  referred  to  a  succession  of  particular 
experiences?  In  other  words,  is  there  any  essential 
distinction  between  contingent  or  empirical  truth  and 
necessary  truth,  or  is  the  distinction  that  exists  between 
them  merely  one  of  degree?  The  problem  as  to  what 
constitutes  reality,  which  is  of  course  involved  in  these 
questions,  is  here  altogether  lost  sight  of.  The  completed 
categories  of  consciousness  which  the  real  world  implies, 
the  entire  synthesis  of  experience,  is  assumed  from  the 
outset. 

The  confusion  between  metaphysic,  psychology,  and 
physics,  so  characteristic  of  the  English  school,  is  present 
from  the  first.  Hobbes  sees  that  sensible  qualities  can 
exist  only  in  the  percipient,  but  he  nevertheless,  as 
appears  in  the  above  passage,  assumes  the  existence  of  the 
mysterious  entity,  a  "  body  without  us,"  which,  in  an 
equally  mysterious  manner  "worketh  upon  the  eyes,  ears, 
and  other  parts  of  a  man's  body,  and  by  diversity  of 
working,  produces  diversity  of  appearances."  Hahhes,_Q£ 
course,  postulates  an  atomism  wViinVi  |ie  bases  upon  tha 
assnu^ptioTi  thattiiatwhich  moves  others  ,nmfit-  also  in 
itself  be  moved  at  least  in  its  smaller  parts,  since  motion 
apart  frmp  Tna.tt^r  or  at  a  distance  is  anj^ppj-^^ibi^^'^^ 
The  senses  of  men  and  animals  are  allected  by  motions 
which  propagate  themselves  from  the  senses  to  the  brain, 
and  from  the  brain  to  the  heart,  whence  the  reverse 
process  takes  place,  which  reverse  process  constitutes 
feeling.  AVe  see  an  anticipation  of  Leibnitz  in  the  asser- 
tion that  all  matter  possesses  potentiality  of  feeling. 
From  feeling  all  knowledge  is  ultimately  derived. 
General  notions,  so  called,  are  nothing  more  than  words 
serving  as  signs  for  an  aggregate  of  similar  objects. 
All  thought  is  merely  the  addition  and  subtraction, 
the  combination  and  separation  of  perceptions. 


182  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

The  original  state  of  man  in  society,  Hobbes  declares 
was  that  of  war ;  this  was  substituted  at  a  later  stage  for 
a  formal  contract  by  which  unconditioned  obedience  to  an 
absolute  ruler  was  pledged  on  condition  that  he,  holding 
the  balance  of  power,  should  protect  individual  members 
of  the  society  to  which  this  contract  was  to  give  birth, 
against  one  another.  This  theory  of  society  was  accepted 
in  substantially  the  same  form  to  that  laid  down  by 
Hobbes  as  axiomatic,  by  almost  all  political  thinkers  till 
the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century,  and  forms  the  basis  of 
that  great  text  book  of  the  French  Eevolution,  the 
"  Social  Contract  "  of  Jean- Jacques  Rousseau.  Morality 
Hobbes  regards  as  the  direct  result  of  the  Political  State. 
That  is  good  which  is  sanctioned  by  the  absolute  power 
in  the  state  ;  the  reverse,  evil.  Religion  and  superstition 
have  this  in  common,  that  they  both  imply  the  fear  of 
imaginary  powers  ;  the  difference  between  them  consists 
in  that  the  fear  or  worship  of  those  imaginary  powers 
which  are  recognised  by  the  state  is  religion,  while  the 
fear  or  worship  of  those  not  recognised  is  superstition. 

LOCKE. 

John  Locke  was  born  in  1632  at  Wrington,  near  Brii^tol. 
He  studied  at  Westminster,  and  afterwards  at  Oxford. 
In  I66i  he  went  on  a  diplomatic  mission  to  Berlin,  which 
lasted  some  twelve  months.  A  few  years  afterwards, 
having  in  the  meantime  resided  at  Oxford,  he  undertook 
a  journey  through  France  and  Italy.  For  a  long  time  he 
remained  as  tutt»r  in  the  house  of  the  Earl  of  Shaftesbury. 
The  '  Essay  on  the  Human  Understanding,'  though 
commenced  in  1670,  was  not  published  until  some  years 
later.  Shaftesbury's  resistance  to  the  absolute  tendencies 
of  James  II.  brought  him  to  the  Tower;  but  being 
acquitted  by  the  jury,  he  repaired  to  Holland,  where  he 
was  followed  by  Locke  in  the  year  1683.  In  consequence 
of  the  revolution  of  1688,  which  placed  the  Prince  of 
Orange  on  the  English  throne,  Locke  returned  to  his 
native  country ;  he  soon  received  an  ofiicial  appointment, 
first  as  "  Commissioner  of  Aj^peals,"  and  afterwards  as 
"  Commissioner  of  Trade  and  Plantao'es."     Locke  died  in 


Erocii  I.B.]  LOCKE.  183 

the  seventy- third  year  of  his  age,  in  1704.  In  addition 
to  the  famous  '  Essay,'  Locke  was  the  author  of  numerous 
treatiises  on  ethical,  political,  and  economical  subjects. 

TJTo  grp.f^.t  principle  of  Locke's  philosophy  is,  that  the 
origin  0^3,^1  imowledoje  is  in  experience,  ana  tnat  the, 
derivation  of  all  concents  is  from  ftxpeneuce.  The  first. 
book  of  his  essay  is  occupied  almost  entirely  with  a 
polemic  against  the  doctrine  of  "  innate  ideas,"  that  is, 
of  ideas  existing  in  the  mind  independently  of  experience. 
_J)id  t.bp  individual  really  possess  such  ideas,  they  would 
be  discoverable  iTi  children  and  savages.  The  fact  that 
tfie  abstract  notions  supposed  to  be  innate  do  not  exist  in 
these  cases,  proves  that  they  are  not  universal,  while  a 
little  consideration  of  their  nature  shows  them  to  pre- 
suppose a  relatively  high  degree  of  culture.  The  case  of 
savages  proves  conclusively  that  there  is  no  single 
ethical  proposition  which  is  regarded  as  binding  by  all 
men  alike.  The  same  reasoning  applies  to  the  elements 
of  our  complex  ideas  as  to  the  ideas  themselves ;  there 
are  none  which  are  innate.  The  understanding;-  js  nrigjp- 
ally  a  tabula  rasa.  The  second  book  deals  with  how  this 
Blank  tablet  is  engraved  with  the  writing  of  experience. 
^J^^^jifL^Z^J^!^!^^  rpppivprs  "  sQ.tp  speak,  of  different  ordexs. 
ofi^perienceTthe  external  senses,  sensation  pro[»br,  and  the 
tRjernaT  sense,  ^v  t.hp.  <^.fl.panity  of -iv^^^^Z/nw..      But  whether 

lafSve  perceive  be  an  outward  or  an  inward  fact,  our 
understanding  is  in  either  case  nothing  more  than  the 
mirror  in  which  it  is  reflected — the  smooth  surface  of  the 
camera  ohscura  which  is  the  passive  vehicle  of  the 
influence  of  the  light  of  experience.  There  are  thus 
ideas  derived  from  sensation,  and  ideas  derived  from 
reflection.  The  capacity  of  an  object  to  produce  an  idea 
in  our  understanding  is  called  its  quality.  Where  the 
idea  is  similar  to  the  state  of  the  object  producing  it,  it 
is  termed  a  primary  quality.  There  are  two  j^rimary 
qualities  in  external  objects  —extension  and  imjienetrability. 
Our  idea  of  an  extended  thing  implies  a  real  externality 
of  the  particles  to  one  another ;  our  idea  of  resistance  a 
real  configuration  of  the  body  producing  it.  But  with 
most  qualities  the  case  is  otherwise.  These  secondary 
qualities^  as  they  a,re  termed,  such  as  colour,  odour,  taste, 


184  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

roTigliness,  smoothness,  beauty,  ugliness,  pleasantness,  and 
unpleasantness,  &c.,  only  indicate  a  certain  relation  be- 
tween our  organs  and  the  object,  but  nothing  existent 
in  the  object  itself.  Indeed,  the  object  has  as  little 
analogy  with  those  ideas  it  produces  in  our  minds,  as  the 
heat  of  the  sun  has  with  the  softness  of  the  wax  which  it 
melts.  It  is  the  cause  of  these  effects  in  us,  but  no  more. 
This  distinction  of  primary  and  secondary  qualities  is  wdth 
Locke  a  cardinal  one.  The  ideas  of  sensation,  then,  are 
the  effect  of  the  qualities  of  outward  things  upon  our 
understanding  ;  those  of  reflection,  the  effects  of  our  own 
inward  states  upon  our  understanding.  Out  of  these 
two  kinds  of  ideas  is  made  up  the  whole  sum  of  our 
knowledge. 

As  the  immense  variety  of  words  is  constituted  of  the 
twenty -six  letters  .of  the  alphabet,  so  the  number  of 
primitive  ideas  out  of  which  all  our  concepts  are  con- 
structed is  relatively  small,  and  may  be  readily  enumerated. 
In  forming  an  inventory  of  them,  it  is  advisable  to  begin 
with  those  derived  from  a  single  sense,  such  as  colour, 
sound,  odour,  &c.,  and  then  to  proceed  to  those  which  are 
produced  by  a  combination  of  several  senses,  such  as  that 
of  dimension,  which  involves  the  idea  of  a  measured  or 
determined  extension  or  space.  We  may  then  proceed  to 
ideas  having  their  origin  in  reflection,  such  as  thought, 
will,  duration,  or  measured  time ;  and  finally  to  ideas 
derived  from  both  sources,  namely,  sensation  and 
reflection,  such  as  those  of  unity,  force,  &c.  The 
complex  ideas  which  are  produced  by  the  combination  of 
these  simple  ideas,  Locke  divides  into  three  classes — ideas 
of  modes,  of  substances,  and  of  relations. 

By  "  modes,"  Locke  understands  "  such  complex  ideas 
which,  however  compounded,  contain  not  in  them  the 
supposition  of  subsisting  by  themselves,  but  are  considered 
as  dependencies  or  affections  of  substances ;  such  are  the 
ideas  signified  by  the  words  '  triangle,  gratitude,  murder,' 
&c." — Book  II.,  Chap,  iii.,  4.  Modes  are  subdivided  into 
simple  or  mixed,  the  first  kind  being  such  as  are  produced 
by  the  combination  of  the  same  simple  idea,  "  as  a  dozen, 
or  a  score  ;  which  are  nothing  but  the  ideas  of  so  many 
distinct  units   added  together,"   and    the    second  being 


Epoch  I.e.]  LOCKE.  185 

compounded  of  various  kinds  of  simple  ideas,  such  as 
"  beauty,"  "  theft,"  &c.  Ideas  of  substances  are  "  such 
combinations  of  simple  ideas  as  are  taken  to  represent 
distinct  particular  things  subsisting  by  themselves,  in 
which  the  supposed  or  confused  idea  of  substance,  such  as 
it  is,  is  always  the  first  and  chief."  —(II.  vi.)  "  Eolation  " 
consists  in  the  "consideration  and  comparing  one  idea 
with  another." — (ib.  vii.) 

The  simple  ideas  which  come  to  us  directly  through 
experience,  are  ektypal,  i.e.  they  always  have  something 
real  corresponding  to  them.  The  complex  ideas,  on  the 
contrary,  since  they  are  the  figments  of  our  own  minds, 
are  archetypal,  and  have  no  reality  corresponding  to 
them.  All  words,  except  proper  names,  are  concerned 
with  the  latter  order  of  ideas,  i.e.  general  or  abstract 
concepts,  and  must  therefore  not  be  regarded  as  represent- 
ing anything  real,  for  there  is  nothing  real  but  what  is 
individual.  Here,  we  may  remind  the  reader,  we  have 
Locke  taking  up  the  parable,  though  possibly  un- 
consciously, of  Occam,  and  the  later  nominalistic  school- 
men. The  third  book  of  the  '  Essay  '  is  devoted  entirely 
to  a  discussion  on  the  question  of  language,  to  the  mis- 
apprehension of  the  true  nature  of  which  Locke  attributes 
most  of  the  fallacies  of  the  metaphysicians. 

One  only  of  the  complex  ideas  does  Locke  admit  to 
denote  any  reality ;  this  exception  is  the  idea  of  substance. 
We  are  compelled,  says  Locke,  whatever  be  the  reason,  to 
postulate  a  substratum  as  that  in  which  the  qualities  of 
things  inhere,  and  which,  although  we  have  no  evidence 
of  it  in  experience,  and  can  even  form  no  definite  idea  of 
it,  we  cannot  help  regarding  as  real.  The  idea  of  sub- 
stance, although  a  complex  idea,  corresponds  therefore  to 
a  reality,  albeit  an  unknown  reality.*  Substances  we 
know  only  by  their  qualities,  and  hence  we  can  only 
classify  them  according  to  their  qualities.  In  this  way 
we  may  divide  substances  into  two  classes — those  capable 
of  thought  or  cogitative  substances  (mind),  and  those  not 

*  We  may  observe  that  Locke's  use  of  the  word  "  substance  "  is  not  that 
of  Aristotle's  ovaiaj  or  of  most  of  the  schoohnen,  but  answers  rather 
to  the  Aristotelian  -n-pccTij  uAtj,  and  to  the  Kantian  thing-in-itselfj  or 
noumenon. 


186  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  Lb. 

■  so  capable  (matter).  We  are  by  no  means  justified,  how- 
ever, in  dogmatically  asserting  tbe  former  class  to  be 
immaterial,  like  Descartes  ;  indeed,  their  susceptibility  to 
decay  rather  gives  colour  to  the  hypothesis  that  they  are 
material  in  nature.  Thought  may  very  well  be  conceived 
as  quality  of  matter.  It  is  just  as  incorrect  to  regard 
the  thinking  substance  as  necessarily  always  conscious 
(another  error  of  Descartes) ;  for  this  is  plainly  con- 
tradicted by  experience. 

The  further  combination  of  ideas  gives  us  cognition 
or  knowledge,  expressed  in  language  in  the  form  of 
the  proposition,  which  may  be  either  instructive  or 
demonstrative,  according  as  to  whether  it  is  immediately 
perceived  or  arrived  at  through  the  interposition  of 
middle  terms.  To  these  two  modes  of  cognition,  may  be 
added  a  third,  namely  :  the  immediate  sensuous  percep- 
tion of  external  objects.  Our  conception  of  God  is  attained 
by  a  process  of  reasoning,  in  other  words,  is  demonstrative. 
It  is  composed  of  ideas  derived  from  our  experience  of 
finite  minds,  with  the  idea  of  infinity,  that  is,  the  negation 
of  limits  superadded.  W  hen  the  constituent  elements 
of  a  cognition  are  universal  notions,  it  is  a  universal 
axiom. 

The  utility  of  universal  propositions  shoiild  neither  be 
over  nor  under-estimated.  We  should  always  bear  in 
mind,  while  emjDloying  them,  that  they  are  ultimately 
mere  abstractions  from  our  experience  of  individual 
facts.  It  is  also  important  to  make  a  distinction  between 
those  general  propositions  in  which  the  predicate  adds 
something  to  our  knowledge  of  the  subject,  and  those 
which  are  merely  verbal  and  identical.  The  statement 
that  a  triangle  is  a  triangle,  or  that  the  triangle  has  three 
sides,  is  a  mere  play  of  words,  since  the  word  triangle  implies 
a  figure  comprising  three  sides  and  three  angles.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  assertion  that  the  outer  angle  is  greater 
than  either  of  the  internal  and  opposite  angles  is  a  state- 
ment carrying  with  it  a  distinct  increase  to  our  knowledge 
of  the  triangle  ;  the  predicate,  in  short,  contains  something 
more  than  what  is  already  contained  in  the  subject. 
This  distinction  appears  hiter  in  Kant  as  that  between 
analytic  and  synthetic  judgments. 


Epoch  Lb. J  LOCKE.  1S7 

Locke  divides  the  whole  of  knowledge  into  natural 
philosopliji  which  deals  with  things,  moral  j)hiloso)jliy^ 
which  deals  with  the  means  Ly  which  the  good  and 
useful  is  attained,  and  logic  which  deals  with  symbols 
and  words.  Locke's  treatise  entitled  the  '  Elements  of 
Natural  Philosophy,'  is  concerned  with  the  first  of  these 
departments.  The  second  is  treated  of  in  a  fragmentary 
way  in  his  '  Thoughts  on  Education,'  in  his  two 
*  Treatises  on  Government,'  and  in  his  '  Letters  on 
Toleration,'  &c.  Nowhere,  however,  does  he  go  into  the 
fundamental  questions  of  ethics  in  any  thorough  manner. 
The  third  or  logical  department,  is  discussed  in  the  '  Essay 
on  the  Human  I'nderstanding,'  as  well  as  in  that  '  On  the 
Conduct  of  the  Understanding.' 

Locke's  views  on  Education  had  a  very  wide  influence, 
and  form  the  basis  of  Rouisseau's  '  Emile.'  His  political 
treatises  breathe  the  spirit  of  the  typical  English  Whig, 
their  ideas  and  reasoning  having  been  since  dressed  up  in 
many  a  Whig  speech  and  pamphlet.  The  resemblance  of 
certain  of  Locke's  political  doctrines  to  those  of  Hobbes  as 
expressed  in  the  Leviathan  would  seem  too  strong  to  be 
accounted  for  by  mere  coincidence  or  contemporaneity, 
although  Locke  himself  disclaimed  all  knowledge  of  the 
Leviathan. 

The  influence  of  the  writings  of  John  Locke,  especially 
the  '  Essay  on  the  Human  Understanding,'  on  the  sub- 
sequent course  of  philosophic  thought  has  been  immense. 
Tliat  it  has  been  so,  is  in  many  respects  surprising, 
considering  how  little  there  is  in  his  works  that  is 
not  to  be  found  in  those  of  his  elder  contemporary 
Hobbes.  His  main  position  indeed  is  traceable  much 
further  back,  and  amounts  to  little  more  than  the  nomi- 
nalism of  Occam  and  his  followers  as  expressed  in  the 
famous  formula  Nihil  est  in  intellectu  quod  nan  ])rius  in 
sensu  fuerit.  The  popularity  of  his  style,  and  the  forcible 
manner  in  which  he  returns  again  and  again  to  the 
charge  in  his  efforts  to  refute  his  adversaries,  real  or 
imagined  (for  it  is  extremely  doubtful  whether  any  thinker 
ever  seriously  believed  in  the  innate  psychological  con- 
cepts which  are  Locke's  particular  hete  noire),  and  to 
establish  his  own  position,  will,  however,  account  to  a  large 


188  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  Lb. 

extent  for  the  hold  he  not  only  obtained  but  kept-  on 
men's  minds.  He  gathered,  so  to  speak,  into  one  focns 
the  arguments  against  the  older  metaphysic,  and  gave  to 
the  empirical  doctrine  of  Bacon  and  Hobbes  a  definite 
psychological  standing-ground.  Locke  was  an  English- 
man of  Englishmen,  alike  in  his  character  and  writings. 
There  is  in  the  latter  all  the  common-sense  force  of  the 
English  character,  with  all  its  lack  of  subtility,  and  we 
may  add,  all  its  honest  contempt  for  the  qualities  it  does 
not  itself  possess. 

We  have  now  to  trace  the  development  of  the  principles 
laid  down  by  Locke,  first  in  the  hands  of  Berkeley,  Hume, 
Reid,  and  the  so-called  Scotch  Psychological  School,  and 
afterwards  in  those  of  the  French  Sensationist  and 
Materialist  School.    . 


BERKELEY. 

Locke's  ideas  were  developed  in  various  directions  by 
his  pupil  Shaftesbury,  by  Clarke,  Hutcheson,  and  others. 
But  the  most  important  among  his  immediate  successors 
from  the  point  of  view  of  the  historian  of  philosophy  is 
George  Berkeley,  born  at  Thomastown  in  Ireland,  in 
1685,  of  an  old  Royalist  family.  Berkeley  studied  with 
avidity  contemporary  philosophical  literature,  especially 
Locke  and  Malebranche.  He  took  advantage  of  a  visit  to 
Paris  to  pay  his  respects  to  the  latter,  but  the  interview 
proved  fatal  to  the  aged  ecclesiastic,  then  suffering  from 
inflammation  of  the  lungs,  who  died  a  few  days  afterwards. 
After  spending  s  )me  years  in  travel,  he  returned  to 
Ireland,  having  been  meanwhile  presented  to  the  deanery 
of  Derry.  This  post  he  subsequently  threw  up,  to  engage 
in  an  abortive  missionary  enterprise  in  the  Bermudas. 
It  was  on  his  return  thence,  that  he  was  made  Bishop 
of  Cloyne.     He  died  at  Oxford  in  1753. 

Berkeley's  standing-ground  is  Lockeian ;  Empiricism 
pushed  to  its  logical  conclusion  in  the  shape  of  a^thoroui^^ 
gwn^  nominalism,  which  denied  abstraction  altogether. 
"KnowIecTgeand  "clemonstration,"  it  is  true,  are  abntit 
universal  notions,  but  it  does  not  follow  they  are  formed 


Epoch  Lb.]  BERKELEY.  189 

by  abstraction.  The  Tiiiivi'rsality  consists  rather  in  the 
*'rchition  it  bears" to  the  partieiihirs  signified  or  repre- 
sented hy  it,  by  virtue  of  which  it  is  that  things  being  in 
their  OAvn  nature  particuhir  are  rendered  nniversal  ""^ 
r^Prineiph'S  of  Unman  Knowh'di^o'  Introduction,  XV.) 
There  is.jiiL-^uek.  thinp;  a,.s  a^umxy^L^al^  idea.  When  I 
speak  of  a  triangle,  says  Berkeley,  l'  do  not  mean  a 
triangle  that  is  neither  "equilateral  nor  scalenor,  nor 
equicrural,  but  only  that  the  particular  triangle  I  con- 
sider, whether  of  this  or  of  that  sort,  it  matters  not,  doth 
equally  stand  for  and  represent  all  rectilinear  triangles 
whatsoever,  and  is  in  that  sense  universal."  That  which  is 
inseparable  in  existence  is  also  inseparable  in  thought.  It 
follows  that  general  names  so-called,  must  be  the  names, 
not  of  general  ideas  (which  can  have  no  existence),  but 
must  be  expressions  by  which  we  represent  classes  of  indi- 
vidual objects,  characterised  by  common  features  with 
special  reference  not  to  the  individual  peculiarities  of  the 
objects,  but  to  their  common  characteristics.  It  is  in  the 
doctrine  of  abstract  ideas  that  this  belief  in  an  inde- 
pendent external  world  ultimately  rests :  "  for  can 
there  be  a  nicer  strain  of  abstraction  than  to  distinguish 
the  existence  of  sensible  objects  from  their  being  per- 
ceived, so  as  to  conceive  them  existing  unperceived  ? " 
(Principles  v.) 

"  If  we  enquire  into  what  the  most  accurate  philosophers 
declare  themselves  to  mean  by  material  substance,  we  shall 
find  them  acknowledge  they  have  no  other  meaning  at- 
tached to  these  sounds  than  the  idea  of  being  in  general,  to- 
gether with  the  relative  notion  of  its  supporting  accidents." 
(XVII.)  Now  all  ideas,  whether  (in  the  language  of  Locke) 
they  be  ideas  of  "  sensation  "  or  of  "  reflection,"  are  nothing 
but  states  of  onr  mind  or  spirit.  Even  the  upholders  of 
the  current  doctrine  admit  with  Locke,  that  the  ideas  of 
colour,  odour,  &c.,  do  not  represent  any  independent  quality 
in  things  outside  us,  but  they  notwithstanding,  incon- 
sequently,  assume  them  to  express  a  relation  to  such 
things.  The  distinction  between  primary  and  secondary 
qualities  is  a  purely  arbitrary  one,  of  no  validity  what- 
ever in  proof  of  the  existence  of  an  external  world,  since 
the  former  can,  by  the  same  reasoning  as   is  used   with 


190  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

regard  to  the  latter,  be  shown  to  have  no  existence  apart 
from  the  mind  perceiving  them. 

The  material  substance  or  substratum,  which  to  Locke  was 
a  necessary  assumption,  falls  away  therefore,  together 
with  the  inherence  in  it  of  the  so-called  primary  qualities. 
It  is  surely  simpler  and  more  rational,  instead  of  imagi- 
ning an  unknown  something  behind  the  qualities  perceived 
in  the  sense-world,  to  acknowledge  that  matter  is  nothing 
but  the  constant  sum  of  these  perceived  qualities — that 
the  thing  is  what  is  perceived  and  nothing  else — or  once 
more,  that  the  being  of  things  consists  in  their  perception, 
that  their  esse  is  percipi.  But  the  assumption  of  a  world 
independent  of  perception  is  not  merely  gratuitous,  it 
involves  a  self-contradiction.  The  notion  of  hardness, 
extension,  figure,  that  is,  of  certain  affections  of  our  minds, 
existing  apart  from  our  minds,  is  plainly  absurd.  All 
v/ould  recognise  the  absurdity  if  any  one  were  to  assert 
the  independent  existence  of  the  feeling  of  pain  caused  by 
burning,  apart  from  its  being  felt.  Strange  to  sa}",  they 
do  not  recognise  that  the  independent  existence  of  the 
fire  itself,  that  is,  of  the  assemblage  of  sense  aifections  or 
ideas  (as  Berkeley,  following  Locke's  terminology,  calls 
them)  connoted  by  that  word,  is  equally  absurd  on  the  very 
Same  grounds.  The  substratum  of  Locke  and  the  philoso- 
phers is  just  as  untenable.  For  did  such  independent  exis- 
tence obtain,  it  is  evident  that  we,  neither  philosophers  nor 
anj^one  else,  could  know  anything  about  it.  In  so  far  as 
the  philosophers  predicate  its  existence,  they  profess  to 
know  something  about  it,  in  which  case  it  is  not  inde- 
pendent of  perception,  since  they  must  have  arrived  at  it 
sooner  or  later  through  perception,  and  therefore  the  same 
reasoning  will  apply. 

Under  no  hypothesis  can  one  escape  the  dilemma  :  if 
the  term  matter  exjoresses  something  known,  it  is  only 
an  idea;  if  not,  it  is  for  us  an  altogether  meaningless 
jDhrase.  To  the  objection  that  the  idea  may  be  the 
copy  of  a  reality,  Berkeley  replies  that  an  idea  can 
only  resemble  another  idea :  "  If  we  look  never  so  little 
into  our  thoughts,  we  shall  find  it  impossible  for  us  to 
conceive  a  likeness,  except  only  between  our  ideas. 
Again  I  ask  whether  these  supposed  originals  or  external 


Epoch  Lb.]  BERKELEY.  191 

things  of  which  our  ideas  arc  the  pictures  or  representa- 
tions be  themselves  perceivable  or  not.  If  they  are,  then 
they  are  ideas,  and  we  have  gained  our  point ;  but  if  you 
say  they  are  not,  I  ap]^eal  to  anyone  whether  it  be  sense 
to  assert  a  colour  is  like  something  which  is  invisible  ; 
hard  or  soft,  like  something  which  is  intangible,  and  so 
of  the  rest."  (viii.) 

The  conclusion  Berkeley  draws  from  his  analysis  is  that 
"  there  is  not  any  other  substance  than  spirit  or  that 
which  perceives."  For,  that  an  idea  should  subsist  in  an 
unthinking  substance  is  a  manifest  contradiction,  to  have 
an  idea  being  the  same  as  to  think  or  to  perceive,  and 
hence  the  only  possible  substratum  for  external  objects  is  a 
mind  or  minds  in  which  they  are  perceived.  The  distinc- 
tion between  ideas  of  sense  and  their  reproduction  in  reflec- 
tion is  that  the  former  are  implanted  in  us  immediately  from 
their  source,  the  divine  mind,  while  the  latter  are  derived 
immediately  from  our  perception  of  the  former.  "  Some 
truths  there  are,"  says  Berkeley,  "  so  near  and  obvious  to 
the  mind,  that  a  man  need  only  open  his  eyes  to  see  them. 
Such  I  take  this  important  one  to  be,  to  wit,  that  all  the 
choir  of  heaven  and  furniture  of  the  eai^h,  in  a  word,  all 
those  bodies  which  compose  the  mighty  i'rame  of  the 
world,  have  not  any  subsistence  witliout  a  mind;  that 
their  being  is  to  be  perceiveei  or  known  ;  that  consequently 
so  long  as  they  are  not  actually  perceived  by  me,  or  do 
not  exist  in  my  mind  or  that  of  any  other  created  spirit, 
they  must  either  have  no  existence  at  all,  or  else  subsist 
in  the  mind  of  some  eternal  spirit, — it  being  perfectly 
unintelligible,  and  involving  all  the  absurdity  of  abstrac- 
tion, to  attribute  to  any  single  part  of  them  an  existence 
independent  of  spirit.  To  be  convinced  of  which  the 
reader  need  only  reflect,  and  try  and  separate  in  his  own 
thoughts  the  being  of  a  sensible  thing  from  its  being 
perceived."  (vi.)  The  existence  of  external  things 
consists  in  their  being  eternally  present  in  the  mind  of 
God,  by  whom  they  are  revealed  to  us.  Hence,  in  a  sense, 
it  is  true  that  they  exist  independently  of  our  mind,  but 
only  so  far  as  they  are  present  in  the  divine  mind.  There 
exists,  in  short,  only  active  entities  (spirits)  whose  nature 
consists  in  thinking  and  willing,  and  ideas  or  modifications 


192  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  Lb. 

of  these  entities.  The  resemblance  of  Berkeley's  doctrine 
to  that  of  Malebranche  in  this  point  is  not  to  be  denied,  but 
the  two  men  approached  the  question  from  opposite  points 
of  view.  Malebranche  never  relinquished  the  Cartesian 
Dualism,  while  Berkeley's  whole  system  is  a  polemic 
against  Dualism. 

Our  knowledge  of  an  object  is  made  up  of  distinct 
kinds  of  sensations,  e.g.  sensations  of  sight  and  sensa- 
tions of  touch.  These  are  absolutely  independent  and 
distinct ;  yet  their  constant  association,  by  means  of 
which  each  becomes  for  us  the  "  sign  "  which  suggests  the 
possibility  of  expressing  the  other,  is  independent  of  any 
control  of  the  precipient  mind.  It  follows  for  Berkeley 
that  this  arbitrary  yet  orderly  and  invariable  connection 
must  have  its  source  in  the  work  of  a  creative  intelligence 
outside  our  own. 

Berkeley,  it  must  be  remembered,  had  a  distinct  aim  in 
view  in  his  philosophical  writings  other  than  the  mere 
search  for  truth,  to  wit,  to  cut  the  ground,  as  he  believed, 
from  under  "  scepticism,  atheism,  and  irreligion."  This 
object  he  thought  he  attained  through  the  refutation  of 
the  doctrine  of  swi  independent  external  world  of  matter. 
Berkeley's  system  may  be  described  as  a  thorough-going 
phenomenalism  or  empiricism.  How  this  system,  which 
was  to  annihilate  all  scepticism  and  atheism,  was  itself 
the  groundwork  of  a  systematic  philosophy  of  doubt,  we 
shall  see. 

The  complete  works  of  Bishop  Berkeley  have  been  more 
than  once  republished,  the  best  edition  being  that  of 
Professor  Frazer,  in  four  volumes,  8vo.,  London,  1873.  In 
addition  to  his  main  philosophical  essay,  entitled  '  A 
Treatise  Concerning  the  Principles  of  Human  Knowledge,' 
in  which  his  leading  positions  are  expounded  at  length, 
he  wrote  'Three  Dialogues  between  Hylas  and  Philonous,' 
containing  the  main  arguments  for  immaterialism  in  a 
more  popular  form.  His  celebrated  '  Essay  Toward  a 
New  Theory  of  Vision,'  contains  an  exposition  of  the 
psychological  side  of  optics  which  has  formed  the  founda- 
tion for  every  subsequent  scientific  exposition  of  the  subject. 
Berkeley  there  endeavoured  to  show  that  judgments  of 
distance  rest  entirely  on  an  empirical  basis.     '  Alciphron, 


Irocn  I.B.]  nUME.  103 


T  the  Mimite  Pliilosopher,'  at  the  time  his  most  popular 
ork,   is   a   dialogue  desig-iiecl   to  ref.ite  the  fashionable 
on-vivant  "freethinker"  of  the  day,  a  ligiire  which  belongs 
that  era, — the  era  of  chap-books,  "  wit,"  coffee-houses, 
ighwaymen — in  short,  which   is  peculiar  to  eighteenth- 
ntury  social  life,  and  heard  of  no  more  after  the  French 
evolution.  In  addition  to  some  mathematical  treatises,  the 
nlj  other  work  of  importance  is  the  '  Siris,'  written  towards 
e  close  of  Berkeley's  career,  in  which  he  starts  from  a  dis- 
ertation  on  the  virtues  of  tar- water,  and  proceeds  to  descant 
n  the  phj^sical  nature  of  things  in  general,  winding  up 
^  vith  a  learned  disquisition  on  theosophy,  Egyptian,  Pla- 
^  jtonic,  and  Christian.     All  Berkeley's  writings  are  inter- 
sting  from  their  quaintness  of  style. 

Berkeley's  position  may  be  summed  up  by  saying  that 
e  put  a  *'  new  question  "  as  to  the  meaning  of  the  general 
'"  bame  "  matter."  Hume,  as  we  shall  see,  in  effect  took  up 
'^  [the  application  of  his  method  at  the  point  at  which 
Berkeley  dropped  it,  and  proceeded  to  inquire  into  the 


meaning  of  the  general  name  "  mind." 


HUME. 


David  Hume  was  born  on  the  26th  of  April,  1711,  in  Edin- 
burgh, at  the  university  of  which  citj-  he  .was  educated. 
He  subsequently  entered  a  merchant's  office  in  Bristol,  but 
finding  the  occupation  little  to  his  taste,  availed  hims^df 
of  a  small  independence  to  migrate  to  France,  where  he 
remained  four  years.  Hume's  first  j)hilosophical  work, 
the  'Treatise  of  Human  Nature,'  was  published  in  1728, 
but  fell  almost  stillborn  from  the  j^ress.  This  was 
followed  in  1741  by  a  volume  of  general  essays,  entitled 
Essays  and  Treatises  on  Various  Subjects,'  which 
attracted  considerable  attention.  Encouraged  by  this 
success,  Hume  ventured  upon  a  condensed  restate- 
ment of  his  philosophical  position,  which  saw  the  light 
3etween  the  years  1748  and  1752.  It  consisted  of  thiee 
portions,  the  'Enquiry  concerning  Human  Understand- 
mg,'  the  '  Die^sertation  on  the  Passions,'  and  the  'Enquiry 
;)oncerning  the  Principles  of  Morals,'  besides  appendices. 

0 


194  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.e. 

The  '  History  of  England '  which  subsequently  made  his 
fame  in  another  direction,  does  not  interest  us  here.  His 
final  work  was  his  autobioo;raphy.  He  died  on  the  26th 
of  August,  1776.  The  'Dialogues  concerning  Natural 
Keligion'  and  the  'Essays  on  Suicide,'  were  published 
after  his  death. 

Hume  closes  for  practical  purposes  the  great  line  of 
British  thinkers  initiated  by  Bacon  and  Hobbes.  We  say 
closes  this  line,  inasmuch  as  there  is  little  or  nothing  to 
be  found  in  the  Scotch  psychological  school  of  Eeid, 
Beattie,  &c.,  which  is  not  a  repetition,  or  at  most,  ampli- 
fication of  what  we  find  in  the  writings  of  these  thinkers. 
Hume's  place  in  the  history  of  philosophy  is  that  of  the 
immediate  successor  of  Berkeley.  His  main  advance  on 
Berkeley  was  this :  the  Anglican  bishop,  while  rejecting 
the  Lockeian  substance — that  is,  the  substratum  of  quali- 
ties— in  so  far  as  the  external  or  material  world  was 
concerned,  never  once  thought  of  rejecting  the  same  con- 
ception with  regard  to  the  internal  or  mental  world.  To 
Berkeley  "  the  only  possible  substratum  for  external 
objects  was  the  mind  or  minds  by  which  thev  are  per- 
ceived." To  Hume,  on  the  contrary,  the  immaterial 
substance  "  mind,"  "  spirit,"  or  "  soul,"  had'  as  little 
justification  in  reason,  as  the  material  substance  against 
■"\vhicli  Berkeley's  polemic  was  directed.  An  achievement 
in  its  consequences  even  more  momeiilous  for  the  subse- 
quent evolution  of  thought,  was  the  attention  Hume  called 
to  the  problem  of  causation,  for  this  it  was  which  Kant 
tells  us  first  directed  his  thought  towards  the  deeper 
issues  of  which  this  was  only  one,  involved  in  Theory  of 
Knowledge. 

Locke  and  Berkeley  had  both  of  them  employed  the  word 
*'  idea  "  for  th^  objects  alike  of  sense  and  reflection.  Hume 
makes  a  distinction  between  impressions  and  ideas.  "  We 
may  divide,"  he  says  (Inquiry,  Sect.  2),  *'  all  the  perceptions 
of  the  mind  into  two  species,  which  are  distinguished  by 
their  different  degrees  of  force  and  vivacity.*  The  less 
forcible  and  lively  are  commonly  denominated  Thoughts 

*  It  is  singular  how  persistently  the  thinkers  of  the  empirical  school 
missed  the  point  uf  the  distinction  between  the  real  and  the  psychological 
order  in  resting  satisfied  with  this  pitiable  makeshift  of  a  dehnition. 


Epoch  I.b.]  HUME.  195 

or  Ideas.  The  other  species  want  a  name  in  our  language 
and  in  most  others ;  I  suppose  because  it  was  not  requisite, 
for  any  but  philosophical  purposes,  to  rank  them  under  a 
general  term  or  appellation.  Let  us  therefore  use  a  little 
freedom,  and  call  them  impi-ession,  employing  that  word 
in  a  sense  somewhat  different  from  the  usual.  By  the 
term  impression,  then,  I  mean  all  our  more  lively  percep- 
tions when  we  hear,  or  see,  or  feel,  or  love,  or  hate,  or 
desire,  or  will.  And  impressions  are  distinguished  from 
ideas,  which  are  the  less  lively  perceptions  of  which  we 
are  conscious,  when  we  reflect  on  any  of  these  sensations 
or  movements  above  mentioned."  Every  idea  has  its 
origin  in  an  impression  or  combination  of  impressions. 
The  having  of  impressions  is  feeling,  the  having  of 
thoughts  is  thinking.  Among  ideas  may  be  distinguished 
those  of  memory,  and  those  of  imagination ;  the  former, 
as  being  nearer  their  sense  original,  being  the  more,  and 
the  latter  the  less,  lively.  The  fundamental  principles 
of  connection  or  association  among  ideas,  Hume  finds 
to  be  three,  namely,  Resemblance,  Contiguity,  and  Cause 
and  Effect.  "A  picture  naturally  leads  our  thoughts 
to  the  original  (Eesemblance) ;  the  mention  of  one  apart- 
ment in  a  building  naturally  introduces  an  inquiry  or 
discourse  concerning  the  others  (Contiguity)  ;  and  if  we 
chink  of  a  wound,  we  can  scarcely  forbear  reflecting  on 
the  pain  which  follows  it  (Cause  and  Effect).  But  that 
this  enumeration  is  complete,  and  that  there  are  no  other 
principles  of  association  except  these,  may  be  difficult 
to  prove  to  the  satisfaction  of  the  reader,  or  even  to  a 
man's  own  satisfaction.  All  we  can  do  in  such  cases  is  to 
run  over  several  instances  and  examine  carefully  the 
principle  which  binds  the  different  thoughts  to  each 
other,  never  stopping  till  we  render  the  principle  as 
general  as  possible.  The  more  instances  we  examine,  and 
the  more  care  we  employ,  the  more  assurance  shall  we 
acquire,  that  the  enumeration  which  we  form  of  the  whole 
is  complete  and  entire."  (Inquiry,  Sect.  3.)  We  quote 
the  above  passage,  as  it  contains  a  concise  statement  of 
the  empirical  method  in  psychology. 

The  objects  of  human  reason  or  inquiry  maj^  be  divided 
into  "  relations  of  ideas,"  and  "  matters  of  fact."     The 

0  2 


196  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

former  alone  are  susceptible  of  demonstration.  All  reason- 
ings concerning  matters  of  fact  are  founded  on  the  rela- 
tion of  cause  and  effect.  And  here  comes  in  Hume's  cele- 
brated doctrine  that  "  causes  and  effects  are  discoverable, 
not  by  reason,  but  by  experience."  With  this  is  connected 
the  categorical  denial  of  any  causal  nexus,  of  any  principle, 
that  is,  uniting  the  cause  with  the  effect.  The  belief  in  this 
nexus  is  attributable,  according  to  Hume,  to  the  fact  that 
custom  or  habit  leads  us  unhesitatingly  to  expect  a  certain 
effect  to  follow  a  given  cause  ;  in  other  words,  it  is  by 
experience  alone  that  the  belief  in  the  necessary  connection 
of  cause  and  effect  is  obtained.  "  The  nature  of  experience 
is  this  :  we  remember  to  have  had  frequent  instances  of  the 
existence  of  one  species  of  objects,  and  also  remember  that 
the  individuals  of  another  species  of  objects  have  always 
attended  them,  and  have  existed  in  a  regular  contiguity 
and  succession  with  regard  to  them.  Thus  we  remember 
to  have  seen  that  species  of  object  we  call  flame,  and  to 
have  felt  that  species  of  sensation  we  call  heat.  We 
likewise  call  to  mind  their  constant  conjunction  in  all  past 
instances."  (Treatise,  Part  iii..  Sect.  6.)  The  effect  is 
totally  different  from  the  cause,  and  can  never  be  discovered 
therein.  There  is  nothing  by  which  we  could  tell  a  priori 
that  the  impact  of  one  billiard  ball  with  another  should 
result  in  the  motion  of  the  second.  Constant  conjunction 
is  all  we  can  predicate  of  this  or  any  other  instance  of 
causation.  It  is  custom  or  habit  alone  which  leads  us  to 
believe  that  the  future  will  resemble  the  past.  Hume  in 
a  similar  manner  disposes  of  the  ideas  of  power,  force 
and  energy. 

Hume's  treatment  of  the  subject  of  the  freedom  of  the 
will  is  based  on  his  theory  of  causation.  Because,  he  says, 
we  are  accustomed  to  believe  in  the  necessary  connection 
between  a  cause  and  its  effect  in  the  external  world,  and 
do  not  feel  any  such  connection  between  our  volitions  and 
the  acts  which  follow  them,  we  regard  our  will  as  free,  in 
contradistinction  to  the  necessity  we  imagine  to  exist  in 
other  instances  of  causation.  This  distinction  Hume,  of 
course,  regards  as  altogether  spurious,  and  therefore 
as  having  no  place  whatever  in  philosophy.  "  All  man- 
kind," he  says,  "  have  ever  been  agreed  in  the  doctrine  of 


Epoch  I.e.]  HUME.  197 

liberty  as  well  as  in  that  of  necessity,"  the  whole  discussion 
concerning  which  "has  been  hitherto  merely  verbal." 
"  For  what  is  meant  by  liberty  when  applied  to  voluntary 
actions  ?  We  cannot  surely  mean  that  actions  have  so 
little  connection  with  motives,  inclinations  and  circum- 
stances, that  one  does  not  follow  with  a  certain  degree  of 
uniformity  from  the  other,  and  that  one  afibrds  no 
inference  by  which  we  can  conclude  the  existence  of  the 
other.  For  these  are  plain  and  acknowledged  matters  of 
fact.  By  liberty,  then,  we  can  only  mean  a  power  of  acting 
or  not  acting  according  to  the  determination  of  the  imll ;  that 
is,  if  we  choose  to  remain  at  rest,  we  may ;  if  we  choose  to 
move,  we  also  may.  Now  this  hj^^othetical  liberty  is 
universally  allowed  to  every  one  who  is  not  a  prisoner 
and  in  chains.  Here  then  is  no  subject  of  dispute." 
(Inquiry,  Part  i.  Sect.  8.)  Being  once  convinced  that  we 
know  nothing  of  causation  of  any  kind  beyond  "  the 
constant  conjunction  of  objects  and  the  consequent  inference 
of  the  mind  from  one  to  another,  and  finding  that  these 
two  circumstances  are  universally  allowed  to  have  place 
in  voluntary  actions,  we  may  be  more  easily  led  to  own 
the  same  necessity  common  to  all  causes."  If  man  had 
but  begun  by  investigating  the  true  nature  of  the  belief 
in  the  connection  of  cause  and  effect  in  the  external 
world,  the  free-will  controversy  would  never  have  arisen. 
The  attack  upon  the  doctrine  of  the  Soul-Substance 
occurs  in  the  '  Treatise  on  Human  Nature.'  Hume  con- 
tends that  this  is  no  less  an  absurdity  than  an  inde23en- 
dent  substance  or  substratum  of  matter.  "  This  question," 
says  Hume  (Treatise,  Part  iv.  Sect.  5),  we  have  found 
impossible  to  be  answered  with  regard  to  matter  and 
body.  But  besides  that  in  the  case  of  the  mind  it  labours 
under  all  the  same  difficulties,  it  is  burthened  with  some 
additional  ones  which  are  peculiar  to  that  subject.  As 
every  idea  is  derived  from  a  precedent  impression,  had 
we  any  idea  of  the  substance  of  our  minds,  we  must  also 
have  an  impression  of  it ;  which  is  very  difficult,  if 
not  impossible,  to  be  conceived.  For  how  can  an  impres- 
sion represent  a  substance  otherwise  than  by  resembling 
it?  And  how  can  an  impression  represent  a  substance, 
since  according  to  this  philosophy  it  is  not  a  substance, 


198  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch   Lb. 

and  has  none  of  the  peculiar  qualities  or  characteristics 
of  a  substance  ?  " 

All  we  know  respecting  the  mind  is  a  succession  of 
certain  states,  seeing,  hearing,  feeling,  willing,  &c. '  The 
assumption  of  a  substratum  in  which  they  inhere  has 
no  warrant  in  experience  and  is  a  purely  gratuitous  fiction 
of  the  philosophers.  Hence  the  question  whether  our 
thought  inheres  in  a  material  or  immaterial  substance 
is  altogether  unmeaning.  We  have  presented  to  us  a 
series  of  impressions  and  ideas.  This  is  all  we  know 
of  matter  or  mind  ;  the  assumption  of  anything  further 
is  an  illusion.  Hume's  speculative  doctrine  thus  re- 
solves itself  into  a  systematic  Scepticism  or  Phenome- 
nalism. The  transition  of  these  impressions  and  ideas 
is  purely  arbitrary.  The  Berkeleian  conception  of  the 
Divine  "  mind  "  having  been  shown  to  be  as  meaning- 
less as  the  Lockeian  conception  of  "  matter,"  it  is  clear  we 
have  no  ground  for  belief — except  what  is  entirely  based 
on  association — in  any  uniformity  of  nature,  whatever. 
The  only  utility  of  metaphysics  is  to  exhibit  the  limits  of 
human  inquiry. 

The  proper  objects  of  abstract  thought  are  quantity 
and  number ;  in  Mathematics  alone  can  we  have  demon- 
stration. "  All  other  inquiries  of  men,"  observes  Hume 
(Inquiry,  Eule  xii.  Part  3),  "  regard  only  matter  and 
existence  ;  and  these  are  evidently  incapable  of  demonstra- 
tion. Whatever  is  may  not  be  ;  n(j  negation  of  a  fact  can 
involve  a  contradiction  ;  the  non-existence  of  any  being  is 
as  clear  and  distinct  an  idea  as  its  existence.  The  propo- 
sition which  affirms  it  not  to  be,  however,  false,  is  no  less 
conceivable  and  intelligible  than  that  which  affirms  it  to 
be.  The  case  is  different  with  the  sciences,  properly  so- 
called.  Every  prop'  ^sition  which  is  not  true  is  there  con- 
fused and  unintelligible.  That  the  cube  root  of  64  is 
equal  to  the  half  of  10  is  a  false  proposition,  and  can  never 
be  distinctly  conceived;  but  that  Ctesar  or  the  angel 
Gabriel,  or  any  being  never  existed,  may  be  a  false  pro- 
position, but  still  is  perfectly  conceivable  and  implies 
no  contradiction."  Questions  of  existence  can  only  be 
proved  by  arguments  from  caiise  and  effect,  and  hence  are 
merely   contingent.     Hume    characteristically   closes   his 


Erocii  I.B.]  HUME.  199 

*  Inquiry  concernino;  Human  Understanding '  with  the 
following  words  :  "  When  wo  run  over  libraries,  persuaded 
of  these  principles,  what  havoc  must  we  make  ?  If  we  take 
in  our  hand  any  volume — of  divinity  or  school  metaphysics 
for  instance — let  us  ask  :  Does  it  contain  any  abstract  reason- 
ing concerning  quantity  or  number^  ?  ^  o.  Does  it  contain  any 
experimental  reasoning  concerning  matter  of  fact  and  exis- 
tence f  No.  Commit  it  then  to  the  flames;  for  it  can 
contain  nothing  but  sophistry  and  illusion." 

Hume  regards  as  much  more  important  than  any  mere 
theoretical  research  that  into  the  basis  of  morals.  Will 
and  action  exhibit  a  perfectly  regular  mechanism,  the  laws 
of  which  can  be  as  clearly  presented  as  those  of  motion 
and  of  light.  He  is  thus  a  thorough-going  determinist, 
as  this  doctrine  is  generally  understood.  The  very 
admission  of  motives  involves  this  principle,  according  to 
Hutne,  while  the  punishment  of  tlie  criminal  is  a  practical 
application  of  it ;  for  if  his  action  were  not  the  necessary 
consequence  of  his  character,  no  end  would  be  served  by 
his  punishment.  This,  however,  does  not  exclude  moral 
jud^iment,  any  more  than  the  fact  of  the  beauty  or  ugli- 
ness of  an  object,  not  being  under  its  control,  hinders 
an  artistic  judgment  on  that  object. 

Hume's  main  division  of  the  emotions  and  passions, 
is  into  "  calm,"  and  "  violent."  "  Of  the  first  kind  is 
the  sense  of  beauty  and  dt-formity  in  action,  composition, 
and  external  objects.  Of  the  second  are  the  passions 
of  love  and  hatred,  grief  and  joy,  pride  and  humility." 
(Treatise,  Book  II.  Part  i.,  sect.  1).  A  further  division  of 
the  "  violent  "  passions  is  into  "  direct "  and  "  indirect." 
"  By  direct  passions,"  says  Hume,  "  I  understand  such  as 
arise  immediately  from  good  or  evil,  from  pain  or  pleasure. 
By  indirect,  such  as  proceed  from  the  same  principles,  but 
by  the  conjunction  of  other  qualities."  Under  the  indirect 
passions  are  included  pride,  humility,  ambition,  vanity, 
love,  hatred,  envy,  pity,  malice,  generosity,  with  their 
dependents  ;  and  under  the  direct  passions,  desire,  aversion, 
grief,  joy,  hope,  fear,  despair,  and  security.  From  the 
primitive  impressions  of  "  pleasure  and  pain  "  proceed  the 
"  prepense  and  averse  motions  of  the  mind."  The  reference 
of  these  to  the  cause  of  the  impressions,  according  as  it  is 


200  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

present  or  absent,  produces  joy  or  sorrow,  hope  or  fear, 
&c.  These  direct  passions  lie  at  the  foundation  of  the 
more  complex,  indirect  ones.  Hume  endeavours  to  show 
tlie  results  of  association  of  ideas  and  impressions,  in  the 
modification  of  the  primitive  passions. 

The  philosopher  cannot  properly  accord  praise  or  blame 
to  moral  action;  ethical  judgments  being  on  the  same 
footing  as  critidal  (a?sthetic).  Hume  is  thus  in  agree- 
ment with  Shaftesbury  and  Hutchison  in  placing  virtue 
in  the  same  category  with  beauty,  and  in  the  hypothesis 
of  a  moral  sense,  as  the  foundation  of  ethical  judgments, 
which  he  asserts  express  nothing  more  than  the 
pleasure  or  the  reverse  which  an  action  occasions  in  the 
spectator.  The  possibility  of  this  is  deducible  from  the 
feeling  of  sympathy  or  reciprocal  communicability  and 
receptivity,  which  unites  us  with  all  sentient  creatures, 
but  especially  our  fellow  men.  The  condition  of  a  moral 
judgment  is,  that  the  action  should  not  be  regarded  as  an 
independent  event,  but  as  the  sign  of  a  disposition  of 
character.  Hume  divides  all  virtues  into  natural  and 
artificial,  the  first  including  such  as  spring  directly  from 
sympathy,  and  which  in  themselves  are  good  and  useful. 
The  second  arise  through  the  exigencies  of  society,  and  are 
hence  conventional,  although  not  arbitrary :  such  as 
probity,  truthfulness,  &c.  Hence  the  idea  of  an  original 
social  contract  is  groundless,  or  rather,  the  reverse  of  the 
facts.  The  societas  becomes  a  civiias,  when  a  definite 
government  arises.  A  dictatorship  becomes  necessary 
when  the  .society  is  threatened  from  without,  from  which 
it  follows  that  the  first  form  of  government  is  absolute 
monarchy.  Since  the  state  mainly  exists  for  the  sake  of 
protection,  there  are  circumstances  under  which  its 
justification  might  cease. 

Such  is  the  course  of  the  evolution  of  thought  that,  as 
we  have  seen,  what  Berkeley  had  intended  to  j)ut  an  end 
to  "  Scepticism  "  and  "  Atheism,"  became  the  most  power- 
ful solvent  of  the  foundation  of  traditional  belief  that  the 
eighteenth  century  produced  in  this  country. 


Epoch  I.b.]  (      201      ) 


EEID. 

In  Thomas  Eeid  we  have  the  progenitor  of  the  large  and 
long-lived  school  of  the  Scotch  psychologists.  His  phi- 
losophy, wliich  started  with  a  polemic  against  Hume,  has 
been  the  fountain  at  which  psychological  Scotsmen 
have  drunk  from  that  time  to  this.  His  writings  have 
been  read,  re-read,  annotated  and  amended  by  four  gene- 
rations of  Scottish  thinkers.  Born  in  1710  at  Strachan, 
in  Kincardineshire,  Eeid  lived  an  uneventful  life.  He 
graduated  in  due  course  at  Aberdeen,  where  he  afterwards 
was  appointed  Professor  of  Moral  Philosophy.  On  the 
resignation  of  Adam  Smith,  he  succeeded  to  the  same  post 
in  the  more  important  University  of  Glasgow.  In  1780 
Eeid  resigned,  passing  the  remainder  of  his  life  in  study 
and  retirement.  He  died  in  1796.  Eeid's  complete  works 
first  appeared  in  1785,  but  have  been  several  times  re- 
printed, the  best  edition  being  that  issued  with  annotations 
by  Sir  William  Hamilton. 

The  secret  of  the  success  of  Reid  among  his  countrymen 
may  be  supposed  to  lie  in  his  professed  appeal  to  common- 
sense,  alike  against  the  scepticism  of  Hume,  and  the 
psychological  idealism  of  Berkeley.  To  Eeid  the  well- 
known  aphorism  will  aptly  apply,  that  he  said  many 
things  that  were  true,  and  some  things  that  were  new  ;  but 
unfortunately,  that  the  things  which  were  true  were  not 
new,  and  the  things  which  were  new  were  not  true.  His 
appeal  to  common-sense,  in-so-far  as  it  meant  anything,  is 
certainly  not  new  ;  his  assumption  that  his  contemporarits, 
Berkeley  and  Hume,  denied  the  fact  of  common-sense,  or 
that  its  dictates  were  practically  irresistible,  is  as  certainly 
not  true,  notwithstanding  some  rhetorical  passages  in 
Hume  which  might  give  colour  to  such  a  conclusion. 

Eeid  starts  by  taking  for  granted  as  axioms  an 
astounding  number  of  propositions,  the  first  and  foremost 
being  the  immediate  dicta  of  consciousness.  "  If  a  man 
should  take  it  into  his  head  to  think  or  to  say  that  his 
consciousness  may  deceive  him,  and  to  require  proof  that 
it  cannot,  I  know  of  no  proof  that  can  be  given  him ;  he 
must  be  left  to  himself,  as  a  man  that  denies  first  principles, 


202  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

without  wliicli  there  can  be  no  reasoning.  Every  man 
finds  himself  under  a  necessity  of  believing  what  conscious- 
ness testifies,  and  everything  that  has  this  necessity  is  to 
be  taken  as  a  first  principle."  ('  Essays  on  the  Intellectual 
Powers,'  I.  2).  In  this  solemnly-expressed  platitude  is 
summed  up  the  whole  of  the  Common  Sense  Philosophy. 
This  thesis,  expanded  into  three  volumes,  may  be  apt  to 
suggest  to  the  irreverent  mind  the  hackneyed  saying,  by 
no  means  always  true,  so  far  as  our  experience  goes,  about 
the  Scotchman  and  the  joke.  Eeid  proceeds  to  "  take  for 
granted,"  as  he  expresses  it,  personal  identity  based  on 
a  "  thinking  principle "  or  mind.  He  sagely  remarks 
that  "  every  man  of  a  sound  mind  finds  himself  under  a 
necessity  of  believing  his  own  identity  and  continued 
existence.  The  conviction  of  this  is  immediate  and  irre- 
sistible ;  and  if  he  should  lose  this  conviction,  it  would 
be  a  certain  proof  of  insanity  which  is  not  to  be  remedied 
by  reasoning  "  (ibid.). 

Eeid  further  as>umes  as  a  first  principle  the  very  point 
in  dispute  with  Berkeley  and  Hume,  namely,  the  existence 
of  external  objects.  Though  he  intends  to  take  up  the 
argument  against  them,  they  would  justly  have  in- 
sisted that  his  whole  attack  was  simply  an  ignoratio 
elencM,  and  that  that  of  which  he  ostentatiously  paraded 
the  assumption  they  had  never  questioned. 

But  after  all  that  may  be  justly  said  in  derogation  of 
Eeid's  claims  as  a  thinker,  it  is  not  to  be  denied  that 
there  are  some  acute  observations  scattered  here  and 
there  throughout  his  works,  and  also  that  he  makes  some 
scores  against  his  more  brilliant  adversaries,  as  for  instance 
(Essays  I.  1),  where  he  touches  the  vulnerable  point  in 
Hume's  doctrine  (which  he  received,  by  the  way,  as  a 
legacy  from  Locke),  viz.  the  formulation  of  the  distinction 
between  the  outer  and  the  inner  orders  of  conscious  states 
as  one  merely  of  "  force  and  vivaci'y."  Eeid  truly 
observes,  "  To  differ  in  species  is  one  thing  ;  to  differ  in 
degree  is  another.  Things  which  diff*er  in  degree  only 
must  be  of  the  same  species.  It  is  a  maxim  of  common- 
sense,  admitted  by  all  men,  that  greater  and  less  do  not 
make  a  change  of  species.  .  .  .  To  say,  therefore,  that 
two  different  classes  or   species  of  perceptions  are  dis- 


Epoch  I.b.]   THE   FRENCH   MATERIALIST   SCHOOL.  203 

tingnished  by  the  different  dco^rces  of  their  force  and 
vivacity  is  to  confound  the  diff«.'ren(e  of  degree  with  the 
difference  of  species,  which  every  man  of  understanding' 
knows  how  to  distinguish."  And  again  :  '\  Common-sense 
convinces  every  man  that  a  lively  dream  is  no  nearer  to 
reality  tlian  a  faint  one,  and  that  if  a  man  should  dream 
that  he  had  all  the  wealth  of  Croesus,  it  would  not  put 
one  farthing  in  his  pocket."  All  this  is  very  apposite 
criticism  on  Hume,  so  ftir  as  it  goes,  but  it  certainly  does 
not  help  the  Keidian  philosophy. 

The  fact  is,  that  Reid  saw  a  flaw  in  Berkeley  and 
Hume,  and  his  whole  system  is  a  bungling  attempt  to 
discover  its  real  nature.  But  it  was  not  iDy  wholesale 
assumptions  and  pragmatical  assertions  that  this  could 
be  done.  Poor  Reid's  sti-Uirgies  to  extricate  himself  and 
human  reason  from  the  meshes  of  Scepticism,  only  resulted 
in  worse  entanglement.  There  was  at  this  time  a  young 
Privat-docent  at  the  Prussian  University  of  Konigsberg, 
who  was  also  trying  his  hand  on  the  same  theme,  but  of 
him  we  shall  hear  more  anon.  Reid's  philosophy  continued 
to  be  taught  in  the  Scotch  universities  by  James  Beattie 
(1735-1803),  Dngald  Stewart  (1753-1820),  Thomas 
Brown  (1778-1820),  &c. 


THE  FRENCH  MATERIALIST  SCHOOL. 

We  now  pass  from  Scotland  to  France,  where  we  shall 
see  the  influence  of  the  same  movement  of  thought, 
namely,  that  originating  with  Hobbes  and  Locke,  ex- 
hibited in  the  writings  of  the  Abbe  de  Condillac,  Bonnet, 
Helvetius,  &c.,  leading  up  to  the  great  French  materialist 
school  of  the  eighteenth  century. 

Etienne  Bonnot  de  Condillac  was  born  in  1715  at  Gre- 
noble. He  published  his  Essai  sur  Vorigine  des  Connaissances 
Humaines,  in  which  he  introduced  Locke  to  his  countrymen, 
in  1746.  His  most  important  work  is,  however,  his  Troite 
des  Sensations  (1754),  in  which  his  special  line  of  differentia- 


204  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

tion  from  Locke  is  shown.  His  Logique  appeared  shortly 
before  his  death  in  1780.  His  completed  works  (Paris, 
1798)  comprise  twenty-three  volumes. 

After  carefnlly  sheltering  himself  from  the  Church's 
censure,  Condillac  proceeds  to  develop  the  thesis  known 
as  Sensationism,  namely,  that  sensation  is  the  one  source 
and  vehicle  of  knowledge, — the  "  thought "  or  "  reflection  " 
admitted  by  Locke  being  nothing  more  than  transformed 
sensation.  This  he  illustrates  by  the  fiction  of  a  statue, 
endowed  successively  with  the  five  senses.  He  first  admits 
the  sense  of  smell,  and  seeks  to  show  the  extent  of  know- 
ledge this  sense  alone  would  suffice  to  procure.  He  then 
proceeds  to  discuss  how  the  world  would  appear  to  a  being 
thus  limited,  on  the  addition  of  taste,  hearing,  &c.  In 
this  he  assumes  that  the  simultaneity  of  an  impression 
with  the  remembrance  of  a  previous  one,  in  itself  constitutes 
a  judgment.  The  sense  of  feeling  is  singled  out  by 
Condillac  from  among  the  rest,  as  being  that  through  which 
alone  is  obtained  the  idea  of  objectivity  proper ;  the 
remainder  only  furnishing  us  with  the  impression  of  our 
own  affections  or  states.  It  is  only  the  solid  which  leads  us 
to  the  knowledge  of  a  world  outside  our  own  organs.  The 
superiority  of  our  sense  of  feeling  primarily  distinguishes 
us  from  the  lower  animals. 

The  ideas  of  good  and  evil,  like  everything  else,  are 
ultimately  traceable  to  sensation.  Condillac  criticises 
Locke's  doctrine  of  the  association  of  ideas,  while  adopt- 
ing it  in  the  main.  liepeated  coincidence  of  ideas  leads 
to  their  being  necessarily  combined.  This  is  the  origin 
of  complex  ideas,  which  may  thus  be  said  to  make  them- 
selves. Nothing  facilitates  so  much  the  fixation  of  these 
complex  or  combined  ideas  as  the  use  of  signs  representing' 
them.  Hence  the  i)Ower  of  language.  The  want  of  the 
capacity  for  language  in  animals  is  as  great  a  drawback  to 
their  intelligence  as  regards  the  combination  of  ideas  as 
their  imperfect  sense  of  feeling  is  as  regaids  the  elements 
of  such  a  combination.  But  though  ideas  maybe  combined 
and  recombined,  it  matters  not  in  how  complex  a  manner, 
yet  they  are  all  ultimately  reducible  to  sensations. 
Penser  c'est  sentir,  is  the  motto  of  Condillac's  system. 

Condillac's  contemporary,  Charles  Bonnet  (1720-1790), 


Epoch  I.b-]  HELVETIUS.  205 

was  independently  working  out  the  same  line  of  thought. 
Curiously  enough,  Bonnet  even  hit  upon  the  illustration  of 
the  statue,  when  he  became  aware  of  the  fact  that  Con- 
dillac  had  worked  out  the  same  idea  five  years  previously. 
Bonnet  was  in  many  respects  more  widely  read  at  the  time 
than  Condillac,  though  his  philosophical  writings  did  not 
exercise  so  great  an  influence  on  the  French  eighteenth- 
centuiy  movement.  Bonnet  was  in  a  sense  the  founder 
of  what  is  known  as  physiological  psychology.  In  both 
his  scientific  and  theological  positions  he  approached 
Priestley.  He  endeavoured  to  show  the  complete  condi- 
tioning of  thought  and  sensation  by  cerebral  and  nervous 
action ;  but,  like  Priestley,  he  sought  to  elude  the  theo- 
logical consequences  of  this  doctrine  by  a  resort  to  the 
hypothesis  of  miracle. 

Claude  Adrien  Helvetius,  another  contemporary  writer, 
(1715-17  71),  further  carried  out  the  ideas  of  Condillac. 
Helvetius  declines  to  regard  the  "  soul  "  as  anything  else 
than  the  sum  of  its  ideas.  Since  all  ideas  are  ultimately 
traceable  to  sensations  or  impressions  of  external  objects, 
all  mental  difierences  which  we  find  among  men  are  the 
result  merely  of  chance  and  outward  circumstance,  the 
most  potent  influence  in  the  formation  of  character  being 
education.  The  end  of  life  is  happiness,  by  happiness 
being  understood  the  greatest  possible  amount  of  animal 
pleasure.  There  is  no  such  thing  as  disinterested  conduct. 
Since  society  is  merely  the  sum  of  individuals,  individual 
satisfaction,  as  such,  contributes  to  the  general  well-being. 
Self-love  is  the  only  motive  of  conduct ;  its  import  in  the 
moral  world  being  analogous  to  that  of  gravitation  in  the 
physical.  It  is  the  lever  of  psychological  no  less  than  of 
practical  action.  All  knowledge  is  dependent  upon  the 
attention  and  study  which  arises  from  the  desire  to  escape 
ennui.  Still  more  obvious  is  it  that  all  practical  action  in 
life  is  traceable  to  self-interested  motives.  From  this  it 
follows  that  no  moral  teaching,  whose  aim  is  not  to  show 
that  virtuous  conduct  is  that  most  conducive  to  individual 
happiness,  is  of  any  value.  The  state,  by  acting  on  this 
principle  in  its  system  of  jurisprudence,  that  is,  by  making 
punishment  attend  criminal  conduct,  shows  the  true 
philosophic  instinct.     Helvetius  is  distinguished  by  con- 


206  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  Lb. 

siderable  literary  facility,  and  his  works  have  been  mure 
than  once  republished  in  a  complete  form. 

Another  influential  writer  of  this  period  was  Julien 
Offroy  de  la  Mettrie  (1709-1751)  who  was  originally  led 
through  observation  of  the  delirium  produced  in  fever,  to 
a  conviction  of  the  absolute  dependence  of  the  psychical  on 
the  physical.  Like  Condillac,  Bonnet,  and  Helvetius, 
whom  he  preceded  by  a  few  years,  he  proclaimed  the 
ultimate  reduction  of  thought  and  will  to  feeling.  Intelli- 
gence would  be  impossible  in  a  man  brought  up  outside 
human  intercourse.  In  ethics  La  Mettrie  was  the  deter- 
mined opponent  of  asceticism,  his  conception  of  life  being 
ably  set  forth  in  his  "L'art  de  jouir."  His  polemic 
against  the  convention  and  hypocrisy  of  human  life 
generally  is  especially  effective.  La  Mettrie  was  a  great 
friend  of  Frederick  the  Great,  who  offered  him  an  asylum 
at  his  court  from  the  persecutions  on  account  of  his 
materialism  which  drove  him  successively  from  France 
and  Holland,  and  at  his  death  composed  an  elegy  on  him, 
which  was  read  before  the  Berlin  Academy  of  Sciences. 
Voltaire  facetiously  styles  him  the  "  Court  atheist." 

A  survey  of  any  department  of  French  eighteenth-century 
literature  would  seem  incomplete  without  some  notice  of 
the  great  names  of  Voltaire  and  Rousseau.  Their  signifi- 
cance for  the  history  of  philosoj^hy  is,  however,  of  the 
smallest.  Voltaire,  whenever  he  touches  on  a  philosophical 
subject,  does  so  from  the  standpoint  of  mechanical 
eighteenth-century  Deism.  Eousseau  is  satisfied  with  a 
sentimental  Deism,  and  is  extremely  bitter  against  the 
materialists.  In  his  Social  Contract,  as  already  mentioned, 
he  develops  in  a  remarkable  manner  hints  which  were 
thrown  out  by  Hobbes,  Locke,  &c.  But  original  reflections 
on  philosophy  proper  are  entirely  absent. 

DIDEROT. 

The  most  important  original  figure  produced  by  the 
French  eighteenth  -  century  movement  in  its  more 
strictly  philosophical  aspect  is  undoubtedly  Denis  Diderot, 
born  5th  Oct.  1713.  Diderot  was  originally  destined  for 
the  priesthood,  but   this  career  he    soon  abandoned    for 


Epoch  Lb.]  DIDEROT.  207 

law,  and  this  again  for  literature.  Diderot  had  a  truly 
encyclopedic  mind — a  mind  eminently  adapted  to  be  the 
organising  power  of  the  great  literary  work  with  which 
his  name  is  most  intimately  associated.  He  possessed, 
moreover,  what  in  Voltaire  and  Rousseau  was  undoubtedly 
lacking — a  considerable  speculative  faculty.  Diderot  may 
be  said  to  have  focuf-sed  the  materialist  movement.  The 
reading  and  translation  of  Shaftesbury's  works  first  shook 
his  faith  in  his  early  creed,  and  resulted  in  the  Promenade 
d^un  Sceptique^  which,  being  impounded  by  government 
before  publication,  did  not  see  the  light  till  after  his 
death.  He  soon  developed  into  a  deist  in  the  ordinary 
sense  of  the  eighteenth-century  man  of  letters,  but  was  too 
acute  to  rest  long  at  this  standpoint,  and  in  the  course  of 
a  few  years  passed  over  to  a  logically  cairied-out  materi- 
alism. Diderot,  after  a  life  of  many  vicissitudes,  alter- 
nately persecuted  and  patronised  in  France,  finding  a 
refuge  at  the  court  of  the  Empress  Catherine  of  Eussia, 
i&c,  died  13th  July,  1784. 

The  pieces  in  which  the  mature  Diderot  is  most  clearly 
exhibited  on  his  philosophical  side  are  the  Interpre- 
tation de  la  nature,  the  Entretien  entre  D'Alembert  et  Diderot, 
and  iife  Beve  de  D'Alemhert,  in  the  two  latter  of  which, 
as  may  be  judged  by  the  titles,  his  friend  and  coadjutor 
on  the  Encyclojjedie,  D'Alembert,  plays  a  prominent  part. 
Several  of  the  articles  in  the  Encyclopedie  itself  are 
rendered  almost  valueless  owing  to  the  fact  that  worldly 
prudence  induced  the  printer  to  modify  them  in  an 
orthodox  sense  before  their  publication. 

Diderot  may  most  accurately  be  described  as  a  material- 
istic monist.  To  him  all  nature  was  one  ;  the  difference 
between  organic,  inorganic,  animal  and  human,  were  only 
differences  of  degree.  There  was  no  such  thing  as  dead 
matter ;  the  molecule  was  no  less  an  active  agent  than  the 
man.  To  employ  an  illustration  of  his  :  "  the  great  musical 
instrument  we  call  the  universe  plays  itself."  It  does  not 
require  a  demiuige  or  deus  ex  macJmid  to  evoke  its  harmonies 
!8,nd  discords.  Matter  is  itself  active  by  its  very  nature, 
iitself  sentient,  itself  conscious,  potentially  when  not 
actuallj^.  In  other  words  matter,  i.e.  physical  substance,  is 
the  ultimate  ground  of  all  existence  ;  nature  is  the  sum  of 


208  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  Lb. 

its  combinations.  One  set  of  combinations  manifests  itself 
as  so-called  inert,  inorganic  matter ;  another  set  as  organ- 
ised sentient  matter  ;  yet  another  as  the  thinking,  feeling, 
willing,  animal  or  human  body.  Diderot  admits,  how- 
ever, an  original  diversity  in  the  primal  constituents  of 
the  various  orders  of  material  existences  :  "  I  term  elements 
the  various  and  heterogeneous  material  substances  necessary 
to  the  general  production  of  the  phenomena  of  Nature, 
and  I  term  Nature,  the  actual  general  result,  or  the 
successive  general  results,  of  the  combinations  of  these 
elements  "  (De  F interpretation,  Iviii.).  Diderot  proceeds  to 
suggest  that  animality  had  from  all  eternity  its  specific 
elements,"  "  confounded  in  the  mass  of  matter,"  that  they 
gradually  became  united,  and  that  thence  vegetable,  animal 
and  human  life  resulted. 

The  materialism  of  Diderot  is  rather  akin  to  the  doc- 
trine of  Anaxagoras,  than  to  that  of  Demokritos  (it  was 
Dynamism  rather  than  Atomism).  It  is  for  this  reason 
that  we  class  him  as  a  monistic  materialist,  in  spite  of 
certain  passages  which  seem  to  make  for  a  contrary  as- 
sumption ;  more  particularly  since  these  are  mainly  to 
be  found  in  the  earlier  work  just  quoted.  For  instance, 
in  the  Entretien  we  read :  "  There  is  but  one  substance 
in  the  universe ;  in  man  or  in  animal.  The  bird-organ  is 
of  wood  ;  the  man  is  of  flesh.  The  canary  is  of  flesh,  the 
musician  is  of  a  flesh  differently  organised  ;  but  both  have 
the  same  origin,  the  same  formation,  the  same  functions, 
and  the  same  destiny."  There  is  a  remarkable  passage  in 
the  B>eve,  where  Diderot,  speaking  through  the  mouth  of 
the  sleeping  D'Alembert,  gives  an  almost  exact  repro- 
duction of  the  doctrine  of  the  Homoiomerai.  "  Everything 
is  more  or  less  some  one  thing,  more  or  less  earth,  more  or 
less  water,  more  or  less  air,  more  or  less  fire,  more  or  less 
of  one  kingdom  or  of  another;  for  nothing  is  of  the 
essence  of  a  particular  being.  No,  assuredly,  since  there 
is  no  quality  of  which  some  being  is  not  participant,  and 
it  is  the  greater  or  less  amount  of  this  quality  which  makes 
us  attribute  it  to  one  being  rather  than  to  another.  You 
speak  of  individuals,  indeed,  poor  philosophers !  Let 
your  individuals  be ;  answer  me !  Is  there  an  atom  in 
nature  strictly  like  another  atom  ?   No.    Do  you  not  admit 


Epoch  I.e.]  DIDEROT.  209 

that  everything  in  nature  hangs  together,  and  that  it  is 
impossible  there  can  be  a  break  in  the  chain  ?  How  then 
about  your  individuals  ?  There  are  none ;  there  is  but 
one  great  individual,  and  that  is  the  All.  In  this  All,  as 
in  a  machine  or  an  animal,  there  is  a  part  which  you  call 
this  or  that  ;  and  when  you  give  the  name  individual  to 
this  part  of  the  whole,  it  is  by  virtue  of  as  false  a  con- 
ception as  if  in  a  bird  you  were  to  give  the  name 
individual  to  a  wing  or  to  a  feather  of  the  wing.  And 
you  talk  of  essences,  poor  philosophers  !  Let  your  essences 
be !  Behold  the  general  mass,  or,  if  your  imagination  is 
too  narrow  to  embrace  that,  behold  your  first  origin  and 
your  last  destiny.  Oh  Architas  !  you  who  have  measured 
the  globe,  what  are  you  ?  A  little  ashes.  What  is  a 
being?  The  sum  of  a  certain  number  of  tendencies.  Can 
I  be  anything  else  than  a  tendency  ?  No,  1  am  advancing 
towards  an  end  (Je  vais  aim  terme).  And  species  ?  Species 
are  only  tendencies  towards  a  common  end  which  is  their 
own.  And  life  ?  Life  is  a  succession  of  actions  and 
reactions.  Living,  I  act  and  react  in  mass  ;  dead,  I  act 
and  react  in  molecules.  I  do  not  die  then  ?  No,  assuredly 
I  do  not  die  in  this  sense ;  neither  I  nor  anything  else. 
To  be  bom,  to  live  and  to  pass  away,  is  but  change  of 
form.  And  what  matters,  one  form  or  another  ?  Each  form 
has  its  own  good  and  ill  fortune.  From  the  elephant 
to  the  grub,  from  the  grub  to  the  sensible  and  living 
molecule,  the  origin  of  all,  there  is  no  point  in  all  nature 
which  does  not  suffer  or  enjoy." 

And  again,  in  the  short  essay  Sur  la  Matlere  et  le 
Mouvement :  "  I  cast  my  ej^es  over  the  general  aggregation 
of  bodies ;  I  see  everything  in  action  and  reaction ;  every- 
thing destroying  itself  under  one  form,  everything  recom- 
posing  itself  under  another ;  sublimations,  dissolutions, 
combinations,  of  all  kinds ;  j^henomena  incompatible  with 
the  homogeneity  of  matter ;  whence  I  conclude  that  it  is 
heterogeneous;  that  there  exists  an  infinity  of  diverse 
elements  in  nature  ;  that  each  of  these  elements,  by  its 
diversity,  has  its  particular  force,  innate,  immovable, 
eternal,  indestructible ;  and  that  these  forces  within  the 
body  have  their  action  without  the  body  ;  whence  springs 
the  movement,  or  rather  the  general  fermentation  of  the 

P 


210  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

universe."  The  force  inherent  in  matter  is  at  once  the 
varying  and  uniting  principle  of  the  whole.  It  will  be 
readily  seen  that  the  materialism  of  Diderot  differs  in 
some  not  unessential  points  from  the  scientific  materialism 
of  the  present  day,  and  also  that  his  several  statements 
of  the  doctrine  are  not  always  consistent  with  one  another. 
The  first  is  but  natural  and  to  be  expected.  Our  admiration 
for  the  luminous  suggestions  of  the  eighteeenth-century 
writer  will  not  be  lessened  bj^  the  few  crudities  from  the 
point  of  view  of  modern  science  which  cling  to  them ;  while 
as  to  the  second  point,  it  must  be  borne  in  mind  that 
Diderot  was  primarily  a  man  of  letters  rather  than  an  exact 
thinker. 

In  method,  Diderot  is  of  course  a  thorough-going 
empiricist.  Materialism  is  the  logical  development  of 
empiricism,  the  tinith  which  it  implicitly  contains.  In 
the  Entretien,  D'Alembert  is  made  to  observe  that  according 
to  the  system  propounded  by  Diderot  it  is  impossible  to 
conceive  "  how  we  form  syllogisms,  or  how  deduce  their 
consequences."  To  this  Diderot  replies  that  we  do  not 
deduce  them,  that  the}^  are  deduced  for  us  by  nature. 
"  We  do  but  proclaim  conjoint  phenomena  of  which  tbe 
connection  is  either  necessarj^  or  contingent,  phenomena 
which  are  known  to  us  through  experience  ;  necessary  in 
mathematics,  rigorous  in  physics  and  other  sciences ; 
contingent  in  morals,  politics  and  the  rest  of  the  specula- 
tive sciences."  To  the  question  whether  the  connection 
between  phenomena  is  less  necessary  in  one  case  than  in 
another,  Diderot  replies,  "  No,  but  the  cause  is  subject  to 
too  many  particular  vicissitudes  which  elude  us,  for  us  to 
be  able  to  reckon  infallibly  on  the  effect  which  will  ensue. 
The  certainty  we  have  that  a  violent  man  will  be  irritated 
by  an  insult  is  not  the  same  as  the  certainty  that  a  body 
which  strikes  a  smaller  one  will  set  the  latter  in  motion." 

We  have  quoted  from  Diderot  at  comparative  length, 
inasmuch  as  he  represents  the  most  finished  literary 
expression  of  the  materialist  movement.  But  the  classical 
text-book  of  this  movement  is  not  to  be  found  in  the 
elegant  and  chatty  dialogues  and  essays  of  the  French 
litterateur,  but  in  the  more  systematic  thouoh  drier  pages 
of  the  Systeme  de  la  Nature^  originally  published  under  ihe 


Epoch  I.b.]  D'hOLBACH.  211 

name  of  the  elder  Mirabeaii,  but  now  known  to  be  the 
work  of  the  Baron  d'llolbach  and  the  habitues  of  his 
salon. 

D'HOLBACH. 

D'HoLBACH,  or  to  give  him  his  full  title,  Paul  Heinrich 
Dietrich,  Baron  von  Holbach,  was  bom  1721,  at  Heides- 
heim,  in  Germany,  and  educated  in  Paris,  where  he  spent 
the  greater  part  of  his  life,  amid  the  wits,  men  of  letters, 
and  "  philosophers  "  of  the  pre-revolutionary  era.  He  died 
21st  February,  1789. 

The  Systeme  de  la  Nature  is  a  systematic  embodiment 
and  exposition  of  the  principles  of  the  dominant  mate- 
rialism. In  it  we  find  the  Empiricism  of  the  British 
school,  the  Sensationism  of  Condillac,  its  pendant,  the 
self-interest  ethics  of  Helvetius,  the  physiology  and  epi- 
cureanism of  Lamettrie ;  the  whole  forming  the  bible  of 
materialism  as  understood  in  France  during  the  eighteenth 
century.  The  only  existence  is  matter,  i.e.  physical 
substance  and  the  motion  that  is  inherent  in  it.  The 
complex  of  all  things  is  termed  nature,  which  constitutes 
the  whole,  inasmuch  as  all  things  stand  in  a  causal  rela- 
tion to  one  another.  Hence  ever^^thing  in  nature  is 
necessary.  The  three  conditions  of  motion  in  the  physical 
world  are  inertia,  attraction,  and  repulsion.  Motion  is 
brought  about  through  the  inequalities  in  the  degrees  of 
attraction  and  repulsion  in  bodies.  The  same  forces 
appear  in  the  moral  world  as  self-interest,  love  and 
hate.  The  only  difference  between  the  physical  and  the 
moral  consists  in  the  difference  between  the  visible  motion 
of  masses,  i.e.  of  complex  systems  of  molecules,  and  the 
invisible  motion  of  the  molecules  themselves.  Thought, 
will,  and  feeling  consist  in  the  molecular  motion  of  brain 
and  nerve  substance.  Owing  to  this  not  having  been 
recognised,  dualism,  or  the  doctrine  of  two  substances,  a 
mental  and  a  material,  with  all  its  train  of  fallacies,  has 
arisen.  Perception  is  nothing  but  the  setting  in  motion 
of  the  molecular  system  of  the  brain  and  nerves  by 
impact  from  without.  It  cannot  be  decided  whether 
sensibility   is,   as   Diderot   suggested,   present   in  every 

p  2 


212  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  I.b. 

portion  of  matter,  or  whether  organisation  is  its  essential 
condition.  Moral  action  is  a  necessary  consequence  of 
temperament,  which  simply  denotes  the  relative  propor- 
tions of  the  solid  and  the  fluid  matters  in  the  system. 
There  is  nothing  more  spiritual  in  love  and  hate,  or  in  the 
numberless  passions  of  which  these  two  are  the  foun- 
dation, than  there  is  in  the  phenomena  of  gravitation 
or  of  impact.  The  only  diiference  is,  as  before  said, 
that  in  the  one  case  we  can  see  the  material  motion 
which  produces  the  phenomenon,  in  the  other  it  is  hidden 
from  us. 

It  was  only  natural,  after  men  had  constituted  them- 
selves into  a  double  existence,  that  they  should  extend 
this  theory  to  the  universe  at  large.  Hence  arose  the 
conception  of  a  God  over  against  the  world,  a  conception 
which  explains  nothing,  does  no  one  any  good,  frightens 
the  foolish,  and  the  folly  of  which  is  manifest  in  the 
fact  that  it  can  be  expressed  only  by  negations.  The 
contradiction  of  ascribing  to  the  deity  human  passions 
and  morality,  after  removing  him  altogether  from  the 
sphere  of  the  conceivable,  is  dwelt  on.  To  the  rational 
man  there  is  no  god  beyond  the  force  which  moves  the 
universe,  appearing  now  as  mechanical  motion,  now  as 
sensibility,  now  as  thought ;  to  him  there  is  no  providence 
but  the  invariable  laws  of  nature.  D'Holbach  and  his 
friends  are  uncompromising  in  their  attacks  on  the 
eighteenth-century  theory,  which  justified  superstition,  on 
the  ground  of  edification.  To  teach  error  for  the  sake  of 
curbing  the  passions  of  men,  is  like  instilling  poison  lest 
strength  and  health  should  be  misused. 

The  doctrine  of  free-will  is  stigmatised  as  a  cunning 
device  for  maintaining  the  credit  of  the  deity  in  the  face 
of  the  evils  of  the  world.  The  adherents  of  the  doctrine 
forget  that  an  uncaused  event  would  suppose  quite  a 
different  world  from  this,  and  that  a  really  free  agent  couid 
be  nothing  less  than  a  creator.  The  immorality  of  the 
belief  in  a  future  life  is  also  insisted  upon  as  tending  to 
the  neglect  of  the  real  world  and  of  its  pleasures  and 
duties.  A  thorough-going  materialism  is  alone  consistent 
with  common-sense  and  human  dignity,  inasmuch  as  it 
frees  men  from  the  degrading  fear  of  imaginary  evils  and 


Erocn  I.e.]  d'hOLBACH.  213 

from  useless  regrets.  The  materialist  has  neither  concern 
for  the  future,  nor  remorse  for  the  past ;  all  that  happens, 
moral  no  less  than  mechanical  actions,  being  the  necessary 
outcome  of  the  nature  of  things.  Vice  and  crime  are  to 
the  materialist  mere  disease.  The  latter  would  supplant 
the  preacher  and  the  judge  by  the  teacher  and  the  phy- 
sician. He  would  be  content  to  make  men  healthy  in 
body,  and  to  train  them  to  see  that  their  own  interest  lies 
in  virtue,  knowing  that  crime  would  thus  become  ever 
more  rare,  until  it  altogether  ceased. 

The  Systeme  de  la  Nature  marks  an  epoch.  Though, 
for  obvious  reasons,  it  has  been  persistently  depreciated, 
its  power,  honesty  and  logicality,  produced  an  immediate 
and  widespread  effect  on  contemporary  thought.  It  suc- 
ceeded in  sweeping  away  the  cobwebs  of  traditional  belief 
from  many  a  mind,  and  in  utterly  discrediting  the  senti- 
mental Deism  then  popular.  As  against  the  inconsequent 
doctrines,  philosophical  and  other,  which  were  opposed  to 
it,  it  was  unanswerable,  while  its  noble  and  humane  moral 
teachings  were  the  inspiring  and  sustaining  power  of 
numbers  a  few  years  later,  whether  in  civil  conflict  or  in 
the  tumbril  carrying  them  to  the  guillotine. 

The  ideas  contained  in  the  Systeme  de  la  Nature  were 
developed  on  their  scientific  side  by  various  savants, 
notably  Cahanis,  Claude,  and  Testutt  de  Tracy.  Cahanis 
(1758-1808)  made  a  distinct  advance  on  D'Holbach  by 
identifying  psychological  processes  rather  with  chemical 
and  organic  than  with  mechanical  action.  Cahanis  is, 
however,  chiefly  famed  for  his  crude  and  singularly 
unhappy  analogy  between  the  cerebral  and  visceral 
systems. 

Of  analogous  nature  to  the  error  of  D'Holbach  in  failing 
to  distinguish  between  organic  or  vital  processes  and 
mechanical,  is  that  which  he  exhibits  in  failing  to  see 
the  difference  between  physiological  and  social  processes. 
He  would  trace  the  existence  of  vice  and  crime  to  certain 
pathological  states  of  the  individual's  body  or  mind,  rather 
than  to  the  economic  and  social  conditions  into  which  the 
individual  is  born. 


(     214     )  [Epoch  n 


MODEEN  PHILOSOPHY. 

SECOND  EPOCH. 
KANT  AND  THE  POST-KANTIAXS. 

INTRODUCTION. 

Eetrospective  and  Prospective. 

We  have  now  passed  in  review  since  the  beginning  of 
the  modern  period,  two  distinct  lines  of  philosophic 
thought,  the  one  springing  from  Descartes  and  his  school, 
and  the  other  from  Bacon  and  Hobbes.  In  the  first  the 
abstract  concept  arrived  at  by  reflection  is  made '  the 
unconditional  test  of  truth,  its  validity  that  is,  is  apart 
from  and  even  outside  all  experience.  Descartes  began  his 
new  departure  in  philosophy  by  the  illogically  constructed 
proposition,  /  think,  thevpfore  I  am.  This  was  the  funda- 
mental axiom  of  all  knowledge,  the  certainty  of  certainties. 
But  what  was  this  /  of  which  Descartes  talked  ?  Upon 
this  question  much  hinges. 

In  the  view  of  the  present  writer,  eminent  authorities 
to  the  contrary  notwithstanding,  the  result  clearly  showed 
it  to  have  been  the  "  internal "  object  arrived  at  by 
reflection — the  individual  mind.  At  least  if  Descartes 
meant  anything  other  than  this  at  starting,  he  certainly 
very  soon  lost  sight  of  it ;  for  the  whole  of  his  philosophy 
proceeds  on  the  foregoing  assumption,  and  proceeds  on  it 
simply  enough.  The  thinking  individual  once  postulated 
as  the  prius,  "  the  clearness  and  distinctness  "  of  its  ideas 
or  abstract  mental  concepts,  becomes  naturally  the  basis 
of  truth  and  its  only  ultimate  criterion,  in  other  words,  the 
reflective  reason  is  the  key  to  the  problems  of  philosophy, 
unalloyed  by  the  baser  matter  of  sense.  The  idea  of  God 
is  attained  ia  this  way,  similarly  that  of  an  independent 


Epoch  II.]         KANT   AND   THE   POST-KANTIANS.  215 

though  created  external  world,  Sec,  Szg.  The  possession  of 
certain  fundamental  ideas  justified  the  construction  out  of 
them  of  a  dogmatic  sj'stem  irrespective  of  experience. 
Malebrauche,  accepting  the  main  Cartesian  positions,  and 
taking  his  stand  on  the  idea  of  substance,  asked  how  two 
distinct  substances,  mind  and  body,  could  come  into  a 
position  of  reciprocal  relation.  This  question  he  answered 
by  constituting  the  Divine  substance  which  was  the 
origin  of  both,  the  modus  vivendi  between  them.  The 
abstract  conception  substance  as  defined  by  Descartes 
became  the  fulcrum  upon  which  his  philosophy  turned. 
This  principle  was  further  and  independently  carried  out 
by  Spinoza,  who,  taking  the  same  concept,  denied,  by  its 
very  definition,  the  possibility  of  a  plurality  of  substances. 
He  accordingly  affirmed  God  to  be  the  one  substance,  of 
which  mind  and  body  or  Thought  and  Extension  were  the 
attributes,  the  reality  and  correspondence  of  which  were 
given  only  in  their  relation  to  this  substance.  Out  of  the 
two  psychologically  "  clear  and  distinct "  ideas  of  substance 
and  attribute,  the  system  of  Spinoza  was  formed. 

Leibnitz,  starting  essentially  from  the  same  principle, 
though  endeavouring  to  give  it  precision  by  sundry 
limitations  and  corrections,  the  principle,  namely,  that  the 
"  clearness  and  distinctness  "  of  the  mental  concept  is  the 
ultimate  criterion  of  all  truth,  evolved  a  pluralistic 
ontology,  the  antithesis  on  this  historical  plane  of  the 
Spinozistic  Monism.  Wolff,  Baumgarten,  Crusius,  &c.,  all 
adhered  to  the  same  principle  of  method,  though  intro- 
ducing various  modifications  into  the  results  of  the 
Leibnitzian  speculations. 

These  schools,  springing  from  Descartes,  are  what  are 
termed  the  Dogmatic  or  Abstract  metaphysical  schools. 
They  are  systems  to  be  received  from  the  hands  of  a 
teacher — what  the  ordinary  man  has  confusedly  in  his 
mind  when  he  rails  at  all  things  metaphysical.  Side  by 
side  with  this  development  on  the  Continent,  there  was,  as 
we  have  seen,  another  going  on  in  this  country.  Bacon 
had  laid  down  the  inductive  principle,  had  pronounced 
the  method  of  all  investigation  to  be  the  observation, 
collegation  and  comparison  of  individual  facts.  This 
Hobbes  had  adopted  in  his  philosophical  investigations, 


216  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IL 

which  consisted  in  the  study  of  what  passed  in  his  own 
mind,  in  other  words,  of  the  manner  in  which  the 
individual  mind  opens  up  (so  to  speak)  to  the  perception 
of  a  fullj^-fledged  objective  workl — of  the  world  as  known. 
Locke,  following  on  this  line,  attacked  the  theory  of  *' in- 
nate ideas,"  as  he  termed  them,  by  which  he  probably 
meant  the  Cartesian  mental  concept,  this  polemic  consti- 
tuting the  framework  of  his  essay.  For  Locke,  the  main 
question  of  philosophy  was,  is  the  individual  born  into  the 
world  with  any  ready-made,  concrete  ideas  in  his  mind,  or 
does  he  derive  all  his  knowledge  through  experience? 

The  question  as  thus  put,  it  was,  of  course,  not  difficult 
to  answer,  and  to  answer  in  the  sense  in  which  Locke  did 
answer  it.  He  said  in  efi'ect,  all  knowledge  is  derived 
from  experience,  or  to  put  it  popularly,  through  the 
senses.  Berkeley  pursued  this  idea  to  its  logical  con- 
clusion on  the  one  side,  when  he  denied  that  an  external 
world  of  "  matter  "  had  any  existence  except  in  a  perceiving 
mind,  for,  said  he,  we  only  know  it  through  experience 
as  perceived,  any  other  kind  of  existence  we  can  only  infer, 
and  as  he  demonstrated,  illegitimately  infer.  Hume, 
accepting  the  conclusions  of  Locke  and  Berkeley,  carried 
them  to  an  equally"  logical  conclusion,  on  another  side, 
when  he  showed  "  mind  "  or  "  soul "  itself,  regarded  as  an 
entity,  to  be  an  illegitimate  inference  from  the  succession 
of  thoughts  and  feelings  which  is  all  that  experience 
gives  us.  Empiricism,  the  necessary  outcome  of  inductive 
psj^chology,  issued  as  necessarily  when  fully  carried  out  in 
pure  phenomenalism  or  scepticism.  The  French  sensa- 
tionists  and  materialists,  starting  from  Locke's  incomplete 
Empiricism,  are  the  counterpart  of  Berkeley's  Idealism, 
their  analysis  being  equally  correct  as  far  as  it  went,  but 
equally  incomplete  and  inadequate.  While  Berkeley 
rejected  the  entity  "matter"  but  retained  the  entity 
"  mind,"  they  got  rid  of  the  entity  "  mind  "  but  retained 
the  entity  "  matter."  On  the  basis  of  his  sole  existence, 
"  mind,"  Berkelej^  sought  to  establish  a  dogmatic  Theism 
or  Spiritualism.  On  the  basis  of  their  sole  existence, 
"  matter,"  they  sought  to  rear  a  dogmatic  Materialism  or 
Mechanicism.  Though  we  are  far  from  placing  the  posi- 
tive results  of  the  two  procedures  on  a  level;   we  must 


Epoch  II.]         KANT  AND  THE   rOST-KANTIANS.  217 

point  out  that,  philosophically  viewed,  they  are  on 
precisely  the  same  plane.  I'he  practical  difference  between 
their  results  is,  that  Berkeley's  work,  important  as  it  was, 
was  mainly  negative,  while  that  of  the  materialists  laid  the 
foundation,  to  a  large  extent,  of  modern  science. 

Both  the  foregoing  lines  of  investigation,  as  will  be 
seen,  started  from  the  individual  mind  as  object.  It 
was  the  "clearness  and  distinctness"  of  the  concept 
that  the  individual  mind  forms,  which  was  the  test  of 
truth  for  the  Cartesian.  It  was  the  reproduction  of  a 
world  alreadj^  assumed  as  existent  in  the  mind  of  the 
individual,  that  was  the  yjroblem  to  be  investigated  for 
Hobbes  and  Locke.  Even  for  Berkeley,  the  "finite 
spirits "  and  the  "  infinite  spirit "  respectively,  in  and 
for  which  alone  matter  existed,  were  concrete  individual 
minds  of  men,  and  the  similarly  concrete  and  individual, 
though  magnified  mind  of  the  creator,  which  was,  so  to 
speak,  over  against  and  distinct  from  them,  as  they  were 
from  each  other.  Similarly  for  the  Sensation  ists  the 
problem  was  the  action  of  the  assumed  material  world 
upon  the  sensory  system  of  the  individual.  Hence  it  is 
that  Spinoza's  Monism  was  such  a  riddle  to  his  contem- 
poraries and  successors  till  the  present  century,  dogmatic 
metaphysicians  and  empirical  psychologists  alike. 

The  main  speculative  result  of  this  evolution,  both 
dogmatic  and  empirical,  was  the  distinction  of  subject 
and  object,  that  is,  of  perceiver  and  perceived,  thinker 
and  thought,  knowing  mind  and  known  world.  This 
was  the  main  issue  of  a  whole  series  of  problems  and 
distinctions  which  had  never  troubled  the  schoolmen  or 
the  ancients,  but  which  rose  up  before  the  seventeenth 
and  eighteenth  century  thinker,  once  he  had  decisively 
turned  his  back  on  the  classical  and  mediaeval  speculative 
landscape.  Not  until  Kant,  however,  did  the  distinction 
receive  definite  expression  and  become  cardinal.  The 
definite  fixation  of  this  distinction,  which  belongs  essen- 
tially to  the  empirical  or  psychological  plane  of  thought, 
discloses  the  inherent  contradiction  in  Empiricism.  Hence 
Kant  represents  at  the  same  time  the  culmination  and  the 
bankruptcy  of  this  line  of  thought.  In  the  Critique  he 
endeavours  to  treat  the  deeper  issues  involved  in  '  Theorv 


218  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

of  Knowledge,'  of  which  he  was  the  first  to  catch  a 
glimpse,  on  the  lines  of  this  mere  psychological  distinc- 
tion. His  success  and  his  failure  were  alike  written  in 
the  history  of  the  subsequent  philosophic  evolution. 

The  above,  then,  was  the  state  of  philosophy  in  the 
second  half  of  the  eighteenth  century.  On  the  one  side 
were  the  dogmatic  metaphysicians,  assuming  the  clearness 
and  distinctness  of  the  thinkers'  concepts,  to  be  a  test  of 
their  objective  truth  or  reality ;  on  the  other,  the  em- 
pirical psychologists,  who  maintained  all  concepts  to  be 
^  originally  derived  from  concrete  experience,  which  was 
hence  at  once  the  source  and  ultimate  criterion  of  truth. 

Kant,  following  a  hint  dropped  by  Hume,  namely,  his 
distinction  between  the  necessity  attaching  to  mathe- 
matics, and  the  contingency  of  "  matters  of  fact  and 
experience,"  was  led  to  put  the  crucial  question,  What  is 
experience  ?  i.e.  what  is  this  concreteness  we  call  reality  ? 
With  the  Lockeian  school,  Kant  admitted  that  every 
concrete  concept  can  come  only  through  experience — 
indeed,  this  was  of  the  nature  of  a  platitude  to  him — but 
his  great  merit  lies  in  having  seen,  if  imperfectly,  the  issue 
which  lay  beyond  this  mere  psychological  question,  the 
question,  namely,  as  to  the  conditions  of  experience  itself? 
In  investigating  this,  Kant  found  that  experience  or 
perception  was  not  wholly  sensuous,  that  the  pheno- 
menon was  more  than  a  ready-made  impression  passively 
received  from  without,  that  it  involved  a  thought  or 
active  element — in  short,  that  the  mere  sense-impression 

hM-^Ist_of.^^-tQJbe-deteimneiOiy--a^^  ^^^"p^^ 

concept  before  it  could  become  experience.  Further 
investigation  proved  this  to  lie  deeper  than  the  object  of 
reflection,  the  individual  self,  with  which  alone  philo- 
sophers had  been  hitherto  concerned.  The  pure  concept, 
which  entered  so  intimately  into  the  essence  of  the 
concrete,  was  universal  and  necessary,  while  all  that 
existed  for  the  individual  as  such  was  merely  emiDirical 
and  contingent.  Kant  proceeded  to  trace  the  categories  or 
pure  concepts,  determining  the  real  (which  he  had  hit 
upon  in  a  somewhat  haphazard  manner)  back  to  their 
source,  and  original  first  principle.  This  proved  to  be, 
not  the  self  or  mental  synthesis  determined  in  time  by 


Epoch  II.]        KANT   AND   THE   POST-KANTIANS.  219 

memory,  bnt  the  I  for  which  time  is,  and  which  Kant 
designates  the  original  synthetic  unity  of  consciousness  or 
apperception.  The  oKl  antagonism  of  Materialism  and 
Idealism  is  clearly  absorbed  in  this  more  thoroughgoing 
analysis.  *'  Mind "  and  "  body "  cease  to  be  separate 
entities,  mutually  exclusive  of  one  another,  and  are  dis- 
closed as  the  same  fact  differently  categorised.  A  short 
sketch  of  the  successive  changes  of  attitude  implied  in  the 
passage  from  the  common-sense  view  of  the  non-philoso- 
phical man,  through  Empiricism  to  that  of  Kant  and  the 
post-Kantian  thinkers,  may  facilitate  an  understanding  of 
much  that  follows,  which,  without  some  kind  of  key,  would 
be  scarcely  intelligible  to  the  reader  unversed  in  the 
matter. 

The  ordinary  man  believes  the  phenomena  of  the 
world  to  be  things  existing  in  themselves  and  apart  from 
their  cognition.  The.  Berkeleian  or  Humean  philosopher 
dispels  this  belief  of  his  by  a  reductio  ad  ahsurdum,  to 
wit,  by  pointing  out  to  him  that  the  thing,  object,  or 
matter,  all,  namely,  that  is  perceived  externally  to  our- 
selves, is  nothing  but  a  congeries  of  affect  ons  or  deter- 
minations of  consciousness,  as  much  so  as  the  thoughts, 
feelings,  and  volitions  which  are  unmistakably  peculiar  to 
himself  as  an  individual.  He  is  therefore  immediately  seized 
with  a  sense  as  of  living  in  a  dream-world,  a  world  of  phan- 
tasms, since  the  outer  world  is  shown  to  have  no  more  in- 
dependence of  the  fact  of  being  known,  felt,  and  perceived, 
than  the  inner.  Both  alike  consist  of  impressions  and  ideas, 
and  he  fails  to  discover — his  old  land-mark,  independent 
existence,  being  removed — any  ground  of  distinction  be- 
tween them.  The  real  table  and  his  recollection  of  the  table 
are  alike  determinations  of  his  consciousness.  But  this 
state  of  mind  cannot  permanently  endure.  The  absurdity 
of  confounding  empirical  reality  and  empirical  ideality  in 
one  category,  the  instability  of  an  attitude  which  logically 
carried  out  makes  the  individual  absolute,  at  once  centre 
and  periphery  of  the  universe,  carries  its  own  reductio  ad 
ahsurdum  with  it.  The  world  refuses  to  be  philosophised 
away,  and  forces  to  a  reconsideration  of  the  problem. 

The  first  departure  from  a  state  of  innocence  established 
one  fact,  namely,  that  a  world  outside  consciousness  is 


220  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  H. 

nonsense  and  a  contradiction  in  terms.  A  return  to  crude 
realism  therefore  is  out  of  the  question.  The  head  and 
front  of  the  offending  diflficulty  is  not  to  be  found  in  the 
first  position  of  philosophy  arrived  at  in  the  departure 
from  common-sense,  which  reduced  the  world  to  a  system 
of  determinations  of  a  feeling  and  thinking  subject.  May 
it  not  lie  in  a  loose  employment  of  the  words  knowledge, 
feeling,  consciousness?  Our  philosophical  neophyte  pro- 
ceeds to  examine  them.  This  examination  proves  that 
these  words  have  been  used  in  a  different  sense  in  the 
premises  of  the  argument  to  that  in  which  they  have  been 
used  in  the  conclusion,  in  short,  that  it  involves  the  fallacy 
a  dido  simpUciter  ad  dictum  secundum  quid.  The  first  posi- 
tion of  philosophy  merely  reduced  reality  to  determinations 
of  knowledge,  or  feeling  and  thinking,  i.e.  of  a  conscious 
Bubject.  The  conclusion  implicitly  or  explicitly  drawn  as 
to  the  illusoriness  of  reality  is  based  on  the  assumption 
that  the  subject  referred  to  is  the  subject  which  is  at  the 
same  time  object,  the  synthesis  determined  by  memory, 
that  is,  reproduced  in  time,  the  individual  mind.  All  with- 
in the  sphere  of  this  latter,  or  psychological  synthesis,  is 
of  course  of  merely  individual  significance,  is  purely  em- 
pirical. The  conclusion  arbitrarily  imports  into  the  terms 
used  a  psychological  meaning,  as  implying  the  completed 
actuality  immediately  present  in  the  individual  mind,  while 
in  the  premises  no  such  limitation  is  contained. 

But,  says  our  empiricist,  I  only  know  of  thought  or 
feeling  as  appertaining  to  myself  as  an  individual.  No, 
interposes  the  speculative  thinker,  who  at  this  stage  steps 
in  to  the  rescue.  In  this  assumption  consists  the  cul-de-sac 
in  which  you  find  yourself  caught.  Vou  assume  know- 
ledge or  consciousness  to  be  identical  with  the  reproductive 
synthesis  constituting  the  individual  mind,  but  analysis — 
nay,  ordinary  experience  itself — gives  the  lie  to  this  as- 
sumption. The  objective  world,  which  3'ou  have  already 
seen  to  be  nothing  more  than  related  feelings  (or  states 
of  consciousness,  if  you  will),  refuses  to  be  reduced  to  a 
mere  series  of  your  personal  feelings  or  states  of  conscious- 
ness. You  and  I  alike  perceive  the  table,  the  same  table, 
not  two  different  impressions  of  an  occult  table  in  itself, 
as  the  imperfectly  developed  empiricist  supposes,  nor  two 


Epoch  IL]         KANT   AND   THE   rOST-KANTIANS.  221 

different  tables,  as  the  psychological  idealist  must  needs 
suppose  ;  else  thought  and  language  have  no  meaning. 
This  objective  ixyint,  at  which  our  consciousness  ceases  to  be 
distinguishable  as  mine  and  yours,  but  which  to  me  and  to 
you,  so  far  as  we  are  individuals,  is  given  as  for  all  possible 
consciousness,  is  not  a  mere  determination  of  me,  i.e.  of  my 
mind,  like  my  personal  thoughts,  feelings,  and  desires, 
but  is  a  determination  of  that  ego  or  subject  for  which 
my  mind  itself  is  object,  of  tlie  J  which  is  never  in  con- 
sciousness, inasmuch  as  it  is  the  subject  of  consciousness. 
The  objective,  then,  is  that  element  or  factor  in  knowledge 
which  though  per  se  extra-individual,  the  individual  makes 
his  own  by  reproducing  in  his  concepts.  Psychology  is 
the  science  which  traces  the  process  of  reproduction.  For 
the  individual  it  is  mediate,  unlike  his  thoughts  and 
feelings  which  are  immediate.  This  necessary  and 
universal  or  object-G\em.ent  in  knowledge  or  consciousness, 
it  is,  which  constitutes  its  reality.  The  term  real  dis- 
tinguishes it  from  the  merely  psychological  element  which 
is  popularly  expressed  by*  the  word  ideal. 

In  accordance  with  the  foregoing,  there  are  three  points 
of  view  from  which  the  world  may  be  regarded.  There  is 
the  standpoint  of  physical  or  natural  science,  which  con- 
cerns itself  exclusively  with  the  objectively  real.  Here 
abstraction  is  made  from  the  self-determining  subject,  and 
the  processes  of  the  production  of  the  real,  as  well  as 
those  of  its  reproduction  in  the  individual  mind,  in  other 
words,  of  the  problems  of  metaphysic  and  psychology  re- 
spectively. The  abstract  real,  the  fully-fledged  object  in 
space  and  time,  but  abstracted  from  the  principle  of 
its  generic  possibility,  and  treated  as  an  existent,  is 
viewed  in  the  same  way  as  by  the  unreflective  common- 
sense  of  the  ordinary  man  and  the  crude  empiricist. 
The  ultimate  expression  of  the  objective  real  is,  j^hysical 
substance,  static  and  dynamic,  the  "  matter  and  motion  " 
of  the  materialists.  To  physical  substance  and  to  its 
categories  of  determination,  and  to  this  alone,  the  whole 
sum  of  things  is  legitimately  reducible  from  this  point  of 
view. 

Again,  there  is  the  standpoint  of  psychology,  which 
views  the  world  simply  as  reproduced  in  the  "mind.' 


222  MODEEN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  U 

This  is  the  standpoint  of  Berkeleian  idealism  proper, 
As  in  science,  "  matter  "  is  treated  as  an  abstract  entity,  so 
here,  *'mind"  is  treated  as  an  abstract  entity,  as  the 
receptacle  of  "impressions  and  ideas,"  also  regarded  as 
independent  existences.  The  universe  of  psychology  is 
*'  mind  "  and  "  ideas." 

Lastly,  there  is  the  synthetic  point  of  view  of  the 
speculative  method,  which  treats  the  world  under  its  most 
comprehensive  and  concrete  aspect,  as  a  system  of  deter- 
minations of  knowledge  or  consciousness — or  rather  of  the 
Subject,  the  I,  or  I-ness,  which  is  the  ultimate  condition  of 
the  possibility  of  consciousness-in-general,  and  w^hich,  as 
such,  can  rever,  per  se,  be  object  of  consciousness,  like  the 
self  or  mind  of  psychology.  On  this  principle  the  con- 
crete-real is  seen  in  the  last  resort  to  consist  in  the 
syntheses  of  relations,  or  /-determinations.  How  from 
this  is  deducible  the  method  by  which  all  evolution  is 
determinable  we  shall  see  later  on. 

We  may  observe  respecting^  the  three  ways  of  ap- 
proaching the  world-problem,  that  the  materia  prima  of 
natural  science  is  corporeality,  extending- resistance ;  its 
universal  form  is  motion.  This  is  the  lowest  term  to 
which  the  universe  is  reducible  on  the  lines  of  "  common- 
sense  "  and  "abstract"  reality,  i.e.  the  universe  in  space- 
and-time.  Outside  this  there  is  no  rational  principle  of 
explanation — in  other  words,  there  is  no  phenomenon  in 
space-and-time  which  cannot  be  expressed  in  terms  of 
matter-motion.  Again,  the  materia  prima  of  psychology  is 
mind,  its  universal  form  being  ideation.  The  psycho- 
logical universe  which  is  in  time  merely,  is  reducible  to 
terms  of  mind  (impressions  and  ideas).  Finally,  the  raw 
material,  the  matter  of  "  Theory  of  Knowledge  "  is  I-ness, 
i.e.  the  potentiality  of  consciousness,  its  universal  form 
being  experience,  knoivledge,  or  consciousness  -  in  -  general. 
"  Theory  of  Knowledge,"  it  will  thus  be  seen,  embraces, 
while  it  transcends  the  two  former  standpoints. 

It  must  not  be  supposed  that  the  f  )regoing  is  to  be  found, 
in  so  many  words,  in  Kant.  Like  all  intellectual  pioneers, 
Kant  clung  to  many  of  the  crudities  of  his  predecessors 
even  till  the  end.  He  never  completely  disengaged  him- 
self from  crude  realism,  or  a'-  least  from  its  survival  in 


Epoch  II.]     KANT  AND  THE  POST-KANTIANS.  223 

the  Lockean  doctrine  ;  for  the  "  things-in-themselves  "  of 
Kant  are  essentially  a  hybrid  between  the  "  substance  " 
of  Locke  and  the  Leibnitzian  monads  with  which  Kant's 
earlier  philosophical  training  had  familiarised  him.  The 
whole  Critique  of  pure  Reason  (Kant's  greatest  work)  is, 
moreover,  cast  in  a  psychological  form,  although  the  true 
nature  of  the  problem  it  is  concerned  with  continually 
forces  its  way  through. 

But  though  the  above  exposition  is  not  expressed  in  so 
many  words  by  Kant,  it  is  indicated  in  every  page  of  his 
writings,  and  was  substantially  the  result  evolved  from 
his  main  position  in  the  course  of  the  post-Kantian 
Movement. 


224  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 


KANT. 

Immanuel  Kant  was  born  April  22nd,  1724,  at  Konigsberg, 
in  wbich  city  be  resided  witb  but  few  intermissions 
throngbout  a  long  life.  He  was  of  Scotcb  descent  on  bis 
fatber's  side,  tbe  name  baving  been  properly  spelt  Cant.* 
Kant  entered  tbe  university  of  bis  native  city  as  a 
tbeological  student,  a  faculty  wbicb  be  subsequently 
forsook  in  favour  of  pbilosopby.  His  first  work  was  an 
academical  essay  entitled  "  Tbougbts  on  tbe  true  estima- 
tion of  tbe  Vital  Powers."  Sbortly  after  tbe  publication 
of  tbis  treatise  be  left  tbe  city,  and  for  several  years 
occupied  tbe  post  of  private  tutor  in  various  aristocratic 
families.  In  1755  be  returned  to  Konigsberg,  wbere  be 
obtained  tbe  position  of  Privat-docent  in  tbe  university. 
He  now  began  to  devote  bimself  in  earnest  to  literary 
■work.  Tbe  Latin  essay  wbicb  preceded  bis  installation  in 
bis  academical  functions,  sougbt  to  mediate  between  Wolff 
and  Crucius.  His  next  important  w^ork,  tbe  '  Greneral 
Natural  History  and  Tbeory  of  tbe  Heavens,'  is  similarly 
designed  to  effect  a  modus  vivendi  between  Newton  and 
Leibnitz.  Various  logical,  metapbysical,  and  scientific 
essays  foUow^ed  in  rapid  succession.  Tbe  Latin  disserta- 
tion "  On  tbe  form  and  principle  of  tbe  sensible  and 
intelligible  world,"  constitutes  tbe  turning-point  in  Kant's 
pbilosopbical  career.  Tberein  we  find  tbe  awakened 
Kant  endeavouring  to  formulate  tbe  problem  of  w^bicb  tbe 
'  Critique '  was  to  be  tbe  attempted  solution.  Tbis  work 
was  bis  test-essay  for  tbe  professorsbip  of  pbilosopby, 
wbicb  be  entered  upon  in  1770.  For  eleven  years  sub- 
sequently, Kant  was  ceaselessly  occupied  witb  tbe  prob- 
lems indicated  in  tbis  dissertation,  tbe  result  of  bis  cogita- 
tions being  tbe  appearance  in  1781  of  'Tbe  Critique  of 

*  The  reason  for  change  of  orthography  assigned  by  Kant  himself, 
is  the  rather  enigmatical  one  that  it  was  in  consequence  of  the 
tendency  of  his  countrymen  to  pronounce  the  name  as  though  it 
began  with  Z  (Zant). 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  225 

the  Pure  Reason,'  a  work  which,  in  spite  of  its  long  in- 
ception, in  actual  writing  out  only  occupied  its  author  five 
months.  This  was  followed  in  1783  by  the  'Prolegomena 
to  every  future  Metaphysic,'  an  abstract  of  the  last- 
mentioned  treatise ;  by  a  second  and  somewhat  mollified 
edition  of  'The  Critique'  in  1784;  by  'The  Foundation 
for  the  Metaphysic  of  Ethic'  in  1786  ;  by  the  'Metaphy- 
sical Foundations  of  Natural  Science'  in  1787  ;  and  the 
'Ciitique  of  Practical  Reason'  in  1788.  In  1790 
appeared  the* '  Critique  of  Judgment,'  a  work  exhibiting 
a  visible  falling-off  in  power,  which  may  also  be  said  oi 
'Religion  within  the  boundary  of  Mere  Reason'  (1793). 
The  last  important  work  from  Kant's  own  pen  was  the 
'Anthropology,'  which  saw  the  light  in  1798.  Sub- 
sequently to  this,  however,  Kant's  lectures  on  "  Logic,"  on 
"  Physical  Geography,"  and  on  "  Pedagogic,"  were  all 
published  by  his  pupils  during  his  lifetime.  Kant  died 
the  11th  of  February,  1804,  aged  eighty. 

Three  complete  editions  of  Kant's  works  have  been 
issued,  that  of  Hartenstein  (Leipsic,  1838-39,  second 
edition  1866)  in  ten  volumes  ;  that  of  Rosenkranz  and 
Schubert,  comprising  a  biography  and  a  history  of  the 
Kantian  Philosophy  (Leipsic,  1840-42)  in  twelve  volumes ; 
and  the  latest,  that  of  Kirchmann  (Berlin,  1868)  in  eight 
volumes,  with  a  supplementary  volume  of  annotations  by 
the  editor. 

"The  Critical  Doctrine." 

The  guise  in  which  the  great  problems  comprised  under 
what  is  termed  "  Theory  of  Knowledge,"  problems  which 
touch  the  foundations  of  consciousness  and  reality,  pre- 
sented themselves  to  Kant,  fresh  from  the  reading  of 
Hume  and  the  Empirical  school,  was  the  at  first  sight 
unpretentious  psychological  question,  "  How  are  synthetic 
propositions  a  priori  possible?"  The  classification  of 
propositions  into  analytic,  or  those  in  which  the  predicate 
is  already  contained  in  the  subject,  and  which  are  there- 
fore virtually  identical ;  and  synthetic,  or  those  in  which 
the  predicate  adds  something  to  the  subject  which  is  not 
already  contained  in  its  definition,  we  have  already  found 

Q 


226  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

in  Locke,  although  in  other  words.  The  distinction  is 
practically  the  same  as  that  between  verbal  and  real 
predication.  Now  there  is  no  doubt  that  all  analytic 
propositions  are  a  priori,  that  is,  independent  of  any 
particular  experience ;  also  that  they  carry  with  them  a 
logical  necessity  and  universality.  There  is  equally  little 
doubt,  that  most  synthetic  propositions  (the  Empiricists 
would  say  all)  have  their  origin  in  particular  experience, 
in  other  words,  are  a  posteriori.  Kant,  however,  found 
certain  propositions,  such,  to  wit,  as  the  fundamental 
axioms  of  mathematics,  and  some  others  of  equal,  or  even 
greater  importance,  whose  nature  we  shall  see  directly, 
which  by  the  "universality  and  necessity"  that  charac- 
terised them,  proclaimed  their  origin,  as  independent  of  any 
number  of  particular  or  individual  experiences  whatsoever, 
in  short,  as  a  priori.  Experience  itself  presupposed  them  ; 
tbey  formed  part  of  the  constitution  of  every  particular 
experience ;  without  them,  experience  would  be  impossible 
or  meaningless ;  it  would  no  longer  he  experience.  This 
universality  and  necessity  was  not  merely  logical,  like 
that  of  analytic  judgments,  but  entered  into  the  constitu- 
tion of  reality.  The  apparently  simple  and  unpretentious 
psychological  query  thus  assumed  a  far  more  formidable 
aspect.  The  question  was  now  nothing  less  than  :  "  How 
is  experience  itself  possible?  "  what  is  this  "  necessary  and 
universal "  element  that  goes  to  the  making  of,  or  that 
underlies  that  real  experience,  which  the  Empiricists  take 
as  a  matter  of  course,  and  about  which  they  talk  so  glibly  ? 
What  is  the  principle  or  principles  from  which  it  is 
deducible,  and  what  is  the  method  and  order  of  deduction  ? 
Such  is  the  problem  to  which  Kant  addressed  himself  in 
the  '  Critique  of  the  Pure  Eeason,'  and  we  may  add  also, 
to  which  the  series  of  German  thinkers  with  whom  Kant 
was  the  starting-point,  and  which  culminated  in  Hegel, 
addressed  themselves. 

The  disadvantage,  as  we  have  already  observed  in  our 
section  on  the  transition  to  Kant,  which  Kant  laboured 
under,  in  attacking  this  problem  from  a  psycho- 
logical base  (so  to  speak),  from  which  he  was  unable 
or  unwilling  to  cut  himself  off,  is  manifest  in  every  page 
of  his  philosophical  wii tings.     A  terminology  derived  now 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  227 

from  the  old  dogmatic  systems,  and  now  from  empirical 
psychology,  hampers  his  thought  at  every  turn,  making 
him  in  some  cases  inconsistent  with  himself,  and  in 
others  scarcely  intelligible.  Kant  sometimes  speaks  as 
though  he  viewed  "  Theory  of  knowledge,"  merely  as 
the  vestibule  of  a  possible  metaphysic,  at  least  he  puts 
it  forward  as  the  preliminary  question,  which  all  meta- 
physicians must  answer,  before  they  can  properly  proceed 
to  construct  a  system,  professing  to  deal  with  the  time- 
honoured  problems  of  philosophy.  He  hesitated  to 
formally  insist,  as  he  might  have  done,  and  as  indeed  he 
frequentl}^  hints,  that  the  answer  to  this  question  exhausts 
the  whole  problem  of  metaphysics,  and  of  itself  constitutes 
philosophy.  He  felt  that  some  place  must  still  be  left  for 
the  old  speculative  inquiries.  With  Kant,  the  chief  end 
of  philosophy  still  remained  the  answer  to  questions,  as  to 
God,  the  Soul,  and  Freewill.  It  is  true  they  were  not  to 
be  answered  in  the  spirit  of  traditional  dogmatism.  They 
had  no  longer  any  theoretical  locus  standi  in  philosophy, 
but  their  determination,  direction,  and  formulation,  in 
the  interests  of  practice,  was  still  its  chief  function.  In 
this,  as  in  other  respects,  the  separate  influences  of  the 
two  sides  of  Kant's  philosophical  education  display  them- 
selves. Empiricism  proclaimed  the  limitation  of  all  know- 
ledge to'  experience.  The  dogmatists  of  the  Leibnitz- 
Wolfian  school,  whose  works  formed  Kant's  earliest 
philosophical  pabulum,  constituted  the  discussion  of  the 
nature  of  God,  of  the  human  Soul  as  an  independent 
entity,  and  of  the  absolute  constitution  of  the  World- 
order,  as  the  sole  end  and  object  of  philosophy.  Although 
Kant  saw  that  "  Theory  of  knowledge  "  was  concerned 
with  nothing  but  experience ;  although  he  saw  that  no 
speculative  science,  as  such,  could  be  concerned  with 
anything  higher  than  this ;  he  nevertheless  felt  himself 
bound  to  make  up  his  account,  in  some  way  or  other,  with 
the  old  questions.  The  ingenuity  with  which  he  en- 
deavoured to  effect  this  without  invalidating  his  main 
speculative  position  we  shall  presently  see. 

Just  as  little  as  the  Empiricists  considered  what  was 
implied  in  that  experience  to  which  they  were  so  fond  of 
insisting  (and  with  justice)  that  our  knowledge  is  limited, 

Q2 


228  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IL 

did  the  dogmatists  consider  the  significance  and  applica- 
tion of  the  conceptions  which  they  so  freely  assumed  to 
transcend  all  experience.  The  former  assumed  experience 
as  a  thing  given,  the  latter  assumed  the  absolute  validity 
of  certain  of  the  concepts  which  experience  presupposes 
as  part  of  its  own  constitution  beyond  that  constitution. 
The  Empiricist  never  stopped  to  ask  himself  what  are  the 
conditions  which  render  experience  possible.  The  Dog- 
matist never  stopped  to  enquire  whether  hisr  abstract 
concepts  had  any  validity  outside  experietx;e ;  or  how  he 
came  by  concepts  which  appear  to  transcend  experience. 

The  thinker  who  wakened  Kant  from  his  dogmatic 
slumber,  as  he  expresses  it,  was  Hume.  Hume  had  shown 
that  the  notion  of  causality  does  not  spring  from  experience, 
but  is  somehow  or  other  imposed  by  us  on  the  events 
which  are  given  us  in  experience.  The  sceptical  attitude 
assumed  by  Hume,  as  regards  metaphysics,  was  merely 
the  result  of  his  imperfect  analysis.  Had  he  not  limited 
his  researches  to  the  conception  of  causality  alone,  he  would 
have  discovered  that  the  whole  of  pure  mathematics 
consists  of  similar — as  Hume  would  have  deemed  them — 
arbitrarily  constructed  syntheses.  This  would  have  sufficed 
to  "  give  him  pause,"  inasmuch  as  he  must  either  have 
straightway  abandoned  mathematical  certainty,  or  have 
reconsidered  his  position  with  reference  to  metaphysics. 
To  profit  by  Hume's  genius  as  displayed  in  his  researches 
into  the  causation  problem,  and  to  repair  the  errors 
arising  from  his  shortsightedness,  we  must  institute  the 
enquiry  into  how  we  come  to  form  such  combinations 
or  syntheses,  which  carry  with  them  "necessity  and 
universality,"  in  other  words,  as  to  the  nature  and  con- 
ditions of  knowledge  or  experience-in-general— an  enquiry 
distinct  from  the  merely  psychological  one,  as  to  what 
falls  within  individual  experience.  Kant,  nevei-theless, 
in  spite  of  his  insisting  on  the  distinction,  is  apt  only 
too  frequently,  to  mix  ujd  the  respective  points  of  view  of 
"  Theory  of  knowledge  "  and  psychology. 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  229 


Transcendental  ^Esthetic. 

Kant  understands  by  "  Transcendental "  all  that  be- 
longs to  the  conditions  or  possibility  of  experience  as 
opposed  to  "  Transcendent  "  by  which  he  understands  that 
which  professes  to  transcend,  or  pass  beyond  experience. 
Transcendental  enquiries  are  simply  enquiries  into  the 
conditions  which  experience  presupposes,  without  refer- 
ence to  the  content  given  in  any  particular  or  individual 
experience.  The  sum  of  such  enquiries  constitute  what  is 
called  Transcendental  philosophy.  Transcendental  ^Esthetic 
'denotes  therefore,  with  Kant,  the  enquiry  into  the  a  priori 
or  transcendental  conditions  of  Sensibility.  These  Kant 
finds  to  be  space  and  time,  together  with  all  that  is 
directly  deducible  from  them.  In  these  two  forms  of 
Sensibility  are  contained  the  possibility  of  the  axioms 
of  mathematics.  They  are  not  given  to  us  through 
the  senses,  like  our  individual  impressions;  these  latter 
constitute  the  matter,  or  the  purely  empirical  element 
in  our  Sensibility.  On  the  other  hand,  space  and 
time  constitute  the  formal  element,  which  helps  to  give 
reality  to  these  impressions.  The  formal  element  of 
space-time  combines  the  manifold  matter  of  sensibility 
into  intuition  or  perception.  Upon  the  matter,  the  sense- 
impression  which  is  received  from  without,  Sensibility 
imposes  its  own  unifying  forms.  In  space  the  manifold 
impressions  of  sense  are  united  in  co-existence,  in  time  in 
succession.  The  a  priori  nature  of  space  and  time  is 
proved  by  the  fact  that  we  cannot  make  abstraction  from 
them  even  in  thought,  as  we  can  from  all  that  is  merely 
empirical.  That  they  are  different  from  conceptions  ab- 
stracted by  the  understanding  is  evident,  since  space  or 
time  do  not  presuppose  individual  spaces  or  times,  but  on 
the  contrary,  individual  spaces  or  times  can  only  be 
thought  of  as  parts  of  the  one  universal  space  or  time. 
Further,  that  they  only  reside  in  our  Sensibility,  and  not 
in  the  object  itself,  is  evidenced  by  the  fact  that  purely, 
spacial  distinctions  cannot  be  described  objectively,  but 
only  with  reference  to  the  cognising  subject.     "  What  can 


230  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY,  [Epoch  II. 

more  resemble  my  hand  or  my  ear,  and  be  in  all  points 
more  like,  than  its  image  in  the  looking-glass  ?  And  yet 
I  cannot  put  such  a  hand  as  I  see  in  the  glass  in  the 
place  of  its  original ;  for  when  the  latter  is  a  right  hand, 
the  one  in  the  glass  is  a  left  hand,  and  the  image  of  a 
right  ear  is  a  left  one,  which  can  never  take  the  place  of 
the  former.  Now  there  are  no  internal  differences  that 
could  be  imagined  by  any  understanding.  And  yet  the 
differences  are  internal,  so  far  as  the  senses  teach  us, 
for  the  left  hand  cannot,  despite  all  equality  and  simi- 
larity, be  enclosed  within  the  same  bounds  as  the  right 
(they  are  not  congruent) ;  the  glove  of  one  hand  cannot 
be  used  for  the  other.  What  then  is  the  solution? 
These  objects  are  not  presentations  of  things  as  they  are 
in  themselves,  and  as  the  pure  understanding  would 
cognise  them,  but  they  are  sensuous  intuitions,  i.e. 
phenomena,  the  possibility  of  which  rests  on  the  relations 
of  certain  unknown  things  in  themselves  to  something  else, 
namely,  to  our  Sensibility."  (Kant's  '  Prolegomena,'  §  13, 
Bohn's  edition.)  By  means,  then,  of  the  forms  of  space 
and  time,  we  combine  the  various  impressions  of  sense 
together  into  a  whole.  Intuitions,  presentations,  or  phe- 
nomena (i.e.  appearances)  consist  therefore  of  formed,  or 
in  other  words,  timed  and  spaced,  feelings  or  impressions. 
It  is,  however,  only  time  that  can  be  predicated  of  all 
phenomena  whatever,  for  although  space  and  time  are 
alike  mere  subjective  conditions  of  our  Sensibility,  yet 
space  only  belongs  to  the  impressions  of  external  Sensi- 
bility, and  does  not  apply  to  our  internal  states ;  on  the 
contrary,  time  is  immediately  only  the  form  of  a  connec- 
tion of  inward  states  or  affections,  in  short,  of  internal 
Sensibility ;  but  since  there  is  no  external  impression 
that  is  not  accompanied  by  the  internal  intuition  of  self, 
time  is  indirectly  the  form  of  external  intuitions  also. 
The  matter  of  Sensibility,  that  is,  the  manifold  impressions 
of  sense  therein,  being  the  empirical  and  casual  element, 
it  follows  that  this  formal  and  necessary  element  of 
space-time  must  be  pure  and  a  priori.  But  if  space  and 
time  are  the  a  priori  forms  of  all  phenomena,  intuitions,  or 
perceptions,  it  is  obvious  that  all  the  temporal  and  spacial 
determinations   of  phenomena  admit  of  prediction  in  a 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  231 

universal  and  necessary  manner.  Now  these  determina- 
tions constitute  the  subject-matter  of  mathematical  science. 
Arithmetic  (and  those  departments  of  mathematics  based 
upon  it)  is  concerned  with  the  repetition  or  succession  of  the 
unit,  in  other  words,  is  founded  on  time.  Geometry  again 
deals  with  the  configuration  of  space.  The  axioms  and 
postulates  of  these  sciences,  inasmuch,  therefore,  as  they  are 
already  implicitly  present  in  our  Sensibility  itself,  are 
universally  and  necessarily  predicable  of  all  that  falls 
within  it.  But  this  also  proves  that  mathematical  pro- 
positions are  strictly  limited  in  their  application  to  the 
phenomena  given  through  sense,  and  in  no  way  apply  to 
things-in-them  selves. 

In  brief,  according  to  Kant,  Sensibility,  with  its  pri- 
mordial forms  of  space  and  time,  is  the  receptive  vehicle  of 
impressions  received  by  it  from  without,  though  of  this 
*'  without  "  we  can  know  nothing  whatever.* 


Transcendental  Analytic. 

Transcendental  Esthetic,  while  exhibiting  the  principles 
of  the  passive  or  receptive  side  of  knowledge  or  experience, 
has  also  answered  the  question,  How  are  synthetic  pro- 
positions a  p'iori  possible,  in  so  far  as  mathematics  is 
concerned  ?  But  as  yet  we  have  only  one  of  the  elements 
constituting  the  completed  synthesis  of  real  knowledge. 
We  have  next  to  treat  of  the  active  element  which  all 
complete  synthesis  or  unification  implies.  It  has  been 
justly  remarked  that  space  and  time,  in  "  the  critical 
philosophy,"  are  the  warp  of  knowledge,  across  which  the 
shuttle  of  thought  has  to  throw  its  woof  before  reality, 
objectivity  or  experience  can  obtain.  A  world  of  three- 
dimensioned  space,  and  of  one-dimensioned  time,  forms  the 
warp.  This  material  is  supplemented  by  the  spontaneity 
of  the   Understanding   or   pure   form  of  thought.     The 

*  This  doctrine  Kant  designates  as  at  once  transcendental  idealism 
and  empirical  realism.  He  claims  that  it  diifers  from  what  he  terms  the 
empirical  idealism  of  Berkeley  ;  inasmuch  as,  while  Berkeley  denied  the 
existence  of  objects  while  admitting  the  existence  of  space,  he  would 
deny  the  existence  of  space  while  admitting  the  existence  of  objects. 


232  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IL 

function  of  the  understanding  may  be  compared  to  tlie 
action  of  tlie  electric  spark,  passing  along  and  illuminating 
the  whole  series  of  sensations.  Sensations,  even  though 
unified  in  space  or  time,  are,  to  use  Kant's  expression, 
"  blind,"  until  they  are  reacted  upon  by  the  Understand- 
ing. The  Understanding  synthesises  them,  and  thereupon 
a  fully-fledged  real  or  experienced  world  arises.  This 
system  of  experienced  objects — the  real  world — is  the 
nature  with  which  science  is  concerned.  Science,  no  less 
than  common  experience,  is  based  upon  the  pure  thought- 
forms  or  categories,  as  Kant,  following  Aristotle,  terms 
them. 

As  in  the  case  of  Sensibility  and  its  product,  intuition 
or  perception,  the  pure  form  or  necessary  element  dis- 
closed itself  after  the  matter  or  empirical  (i.e.  contingent) 
element  had  been  abstracted  from,  so  here  the  pure  con- 
cept or  category  is  arrived  at,  by  abstracting  from  the 
matter  of  the  logical  judgment ;  we  then  see  the  necessary 
conditions  which  every  judgment  presupposes.  The  clue 
to  the  discovery  of  these  universal  categories  of  conscious- 
ness Kant  thus  found  in  the  ordinary  logical  table  of 
judgments. 

The  following  is  the  list  as  given  by  Kant : — 

Logical  Table  of  the  Judgments. 

1.  2. 

According  to  Quantity,  According  to  Quality, 

Universal.  Affirmative. 

Particular.  Negative. 

Singular.  Infinitive. 

3.  4. 

According  to  Relation.  According  to  Modality, 

Categorical.  Problematical. 

Hypothetical.  Assertoricul. 

Disjunctive.  Apodictic. 

Parallel  to  this  table  runs  the  Transcendental  table 
of  the  categories  which  Kant  derived  from  it,  but  of 
which  the  logical  judgments  are,  or  should  be  if  Kant's 
derivation  is  correct,  the  applied  form. 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  233 

Transcendental  Table  of  the  Conceptions  of  the 

Understanding. 

1.  2. 

According  to  Quantity.  According  to  Quality. 

Unity.  Reality 

Plurality.  Negation. 

Totality.  Limitation. 

3.  4. 

According  to  Relation.  According  to  Modality. 

Substance  and  accident.  Possibility. 

Cause  and  effect.  Actuality. 

Community  (action  and  reaction).  Necessity. 

As  a  matter  of  fact,  Kant's  derivation  of  the  categories 
from  the  judgments  is  in  many  cases  forced  and  arbitrary.* 
The  distinctions  contained  in  the  original  table  are  them- 
selves often  of  doubtful  value,  and  sometimes  altogether 
untenable.  This,  however,  does  not  affect  the  philoso- 
phical importance  of  Kant's  analysis.  The  accuracy  or 
inaccuracy  of  the  list  of  categories  furnished,  does  not 
touch  the  point  that  experience  is  determined  by  thought 
in  a  manner  at  least  generally  corresponding  to  the 
Kantian  categories. 

But  to  proceed  with  our  analysis.  Having  gathered 
together  these  categories  in  the  somewhat  hap-hazard 
manner  we  have  seen,  it  remained  for  Kant  to  justify 
their  place  in  a  doctrine  professing  to  be  systematic  by 
deducing  them  from  some  primary  datum  or  principle  of 
consciousness.  This  he  seeks  to  effect  in  his  sections  on 
the  deduction  of  the  categories,  one  of  the  most  important 
portions  of  the  '  Critique.'  It  is  necessary  to  remember 
that  the  deduction  is  no  demonstration,  in  the  ordinary 
sense  of  the  word,  but  like  every  other  "  transcendental " 
exposition,  is  designed  to  show  that  reality  or  experience 
itself  presupposes  the  successive  stages  of  the  argument 
as  its  necessary  conditions ;  that  on  ultimate  analysis,  all 
knowledge   is   resolvable   into   these,   as   its   constituent 

*  The  student  may  observe  that  in  the  categoiies  of  Quantity  and 
Qtiality  (the  mathematical  categories,  as  Kant  termed  them),  the 
order  of  the  corresponding  table  of  judgments  is  reversed. 


234  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

elements.  The  sections  on  the  deduction  of  the  categories 
are  very  different  in  the  two  editions  of  the  '  Critique.' 
It  is  here  that  the  crucial  point,  separating  Theory  of 
Knowledge  from  Psychology,  is  to  be  found. 

We  have  seen  that  the  phenomena  furnished  by  the 
Sensibility  to  the  Understanding  are  simply  presentments 
or  presentations,  in  other  words,  determinations  or  limita- 
tions of  Sensibility.  Looking  at  the  question  from  the 
standpoint  of  Psychology,  with  its  hard  and  fast  distinc- 
tion of  subject  and  object,  inner  and  outer,  mind  and 
matter,  it  seems  utterly  enigmatical  that  I  should  have  a 
right  to  affirm  universal  or  objective  validity  of  the 
categories  ;  for  instance,  to  say  that  the  conception  of 
cause  and  effect  can  never  be  contradicted  by  any  expe- 
rience. "  There  are  only  two  possible  ways,"  says  Kant, 
*'  in  which  synthetical  representation  and  its  objects  can 
coincide  with  and  relate  necessarily  to  each  other,  and,  as 
it  were,  meet  together.  Either  the  object  alone  makes  the 
representation  possible,  or  the  representation  alone  makes 
the  object  possible.  In  the  former  case,  the  relation  be- 
tween them  is  only  empirical,  and  an  a  priori  representa- 
tion is  impossible.  And  this  is  the  case  with  phenomena, 
as  regards  that  in  them  which  is  referable  to  mere  sensa- 
tion. In  the  latter  case — although  representation  alone 
(for  of  its  causality,  by  means  of  the  will,  we  do  not  here 
speak)  does  not  produce  the  object  as  to  its  existence,  it 
must  nevertheless  be  a  priori  determinative  in  regard  to 
the  object,  if  it  is  only  by  means  of  the  representation 
that  we  can  cognise  any  thing  as  an  object."  (Kant's 
'  Critique,'  p.  77  :  Bohn's  edition.) 

We  have,  it  must  be  remembered,  to  distinguish  between 
two  distinct  processes ;  two  presentations  may  combine 
themselves  in  an  individual  consciousness,  in  a  certain 
time-order,  i.e.  in  the  empirical  ego,  which  itself  consists 
simply  in  a  synthesised  series  of  impressions  on  the 
internal  sense  determined  in  time.  In  this  case  the  judg- 
ment, together  with  its  contained  conception,  its  root,  is 
merely  a,  judgment  of  perception.  These  have  merely  a  sub- 
jective and  individual  validity ;  in  other  words,  they  are 
purely  empirical  and  contingent.  Or,  on  the  other  hand, 
they  may  be  combined  in  a  manner  valid  not  alone  for 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  235 

the  individual  consciousness,  but  for  all  possible  conscious- 
ness ;  that  is,  they  may  be  combined  in  a  consciousness-in- 
general.  "  The  business  of  the  senses,"  says  Kant,  "  is  to 
intuite,  that  of  the  understanding  to  think.  But  to  think 
is  to  unite  presentations  in  a  consciousness.  This  union  is 
either  merely  relative  to  the  subject,  and  is  contingent 
and  subjective,  or  is  given  unconditionally,  and  is  neces- 
sary or  objective.  The  union  of  presentations  in  a  con- 
sciousness is  judgment.  Thinking,  then,  is  the  same  aa 
judging,  or  referring  presentations  to  judgments  in  general. 
Hence,  judgments  are  either  entirely  subjective,  when 
presentations  are  solely  referred  to  a  consciousness  in  ono 
subject,  and  are  therein  united,  or  they  are  objective 
when  they  are  united  in  a  consciousness  in  general,  that 
is,  are  necessarily  united  therein.  The  logical  momenta 
of  all  judgments  are  so  many  possible  modes  of  uniting 
presentations  in  a  consciousness.  But  if  they  serve  as 
conceptions  of  the  necessary  union  of  the  same  in  a  con- 
sciousness, they  are  therefore  principles  of  objectively 
valid  judgments.  This  union  in  a  consciousness  is  either 
analytic  by  identity,  or  synthetic  by  the  combination  and 
addition  of  different  presentations  to  one  another.  Ex- 
perience consists  in  the  synthetic  connection  of  phenomena 
(perceptions)  in  a  consciousness,  in  so  far  as  this  is  neces- 
sary. Hence,  pure  conceptions  of  the  understanding  are 
those  under  which  all  perceptions  must  be  previously  sub- 
sumed, before  they  can  serve  as  judgments  of  experience, 
in  which  the  synthetic  unity  of  perceptions  is  presented 
as  necessary  and  universal."  (Kant's  'Prolegomena,* 
§  22  :  Bohn's  edition.) 

But  these  pure  conceptions  of  the  understanding,  to 
which  perceptions  are  immediately  referred,  before  they 
can  become  real  or  objective,  themselves  presuppose  syn- 
thetic processes  lying  (so  to  speak)  still  deeper  in  the 
nature  of  consciousness.  These  are  the  synthesis  of  appre- 
hension in  intuition,  of  reproduction  in  the  imagination,  and 
of  recognition  in  the  conception  itself.  The  material  origi- 
nally supplied  by  sense  requires  a  unification  other  than 
that  furnished  by  the  passive  forms  of  sense.  This 
unity  is  afforded  in  the  primary  act  of  intuiting,  or 
perceiving    the    sense-manifold    furnished   in    time    and 


236  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

space.  Each  impression  given  in  an  instant  of  time 
would  be  lost,  were  it  not  gathered  up  in  the  act  of 
intuition,  and  connected  with  those  which  precede  and 
follow  it.  This  is  what  Kant  terms  the  synthesis  of  ajjpre- 
hension.  More  than  this  is  necessary,  if  a  unity  is  to  be 
formed  out  of  these  several  points  of  perception.  To  this 
end  they  must  be  reproduced  in  the  imagination  and 
retained  for  combination  with  fresh  impressions.  This 
synthesis  of  reproduction  in  imagination  is  therefore  in- 
separably bound  up  with  the  foregoing  synthesis  of  appre- 
hension, liastly,  before  the  completed  categories  can  come 
into  operation  a  further  step  has  to  be  traversed.  "  With- 
out the  consciousness,"  says  Kant  (the  passage,  I  may 
mention,  occurs  in  the  first  edition  of  the  '  Critique ' 
only),  *'  that  what  we  think  is  the  same  as  what  we 
thought  a  moment  before,  all  reproduction  in  the  series 
of  presentations  would  be  in  vain.  For  there  would  be 
a  new  presentation  in  the  actual  state,  not  in  any  way 
belonging  to  the  act  whereby  it  must  have  been  gradu- 
ally created,  and  the  manifold  therein  would  still  not 
constitute  a  whole,  inasmuch  as  it  would  lack  the  unity 
which  this  consciousness  alone  can  give  it.  If  I  forget 
in  counting  that  the  unities  which  are  at  present  before 
my  senses  have  been  successively  added  together  by  me, 
I  should  not  understand  the  creation  of  multitude  through 
this  successive  addition  of  one  to  one,  and  hence  I  should 
not  understand  number,  a  conception  consisting  simply 
in  the  consciousness  of  this  unity  in  synthesis."  The 
last-named  consciousness  is  what  Kant  terms  the  recog- 
nition in  the  conception,  which  is  necessarj^  before  the  cate- 
gories can  obtain.  Now  we  need  scarcely  say  that  all 
these  acts  or  processes  are  a  priori,  that  is,  precede  all 
particular  experience;  that  they  are  further  removed 
from  the  latter,  even  than  the  categories  themselves,  not- 
withstanding that  each  of  them  can  be  distinguished 
empirically,  that  is,  in  its  application  to  given  experience. 
The  two  first  unite  empirically  in  perception,  and  the 
third  gives  us  the  empirical  consciousness  of  the  identity 
of  these  reproduced  perceptions,  T\dth  the  phenomena 
whereby  they  were  originally  given. 

But  deeper  than  any  of  these  syntheses,  deeper  even 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  237 

than  the  unitT/  of  ajjprehension  in  sense,  lies  the  original 
synthesis  of  the  consciousness,  the  uniti/  of  apperception  as 
Kant  terms  it.  All  the  unifying  acts  we  have  heen 
considering  find  their  ground  in  time;  this  one,  on  the 
contrary,  is  not  in  time,  but  time  is  in  it.  The  necessary 
and  universal  identity  of  the  knowing  subject  in  respect 
of  all  presentations,  or  determinations  of  consciousness 
whatsoever,  is  the  necessary  condition  of  the  possibility 
of  consciousness.  This  primary  synthesis  is  identified  by 
Kant  with  the  productive  or  pure  ego,  the  ultimate 
datum  of  "  theory  of  knowledge,"  as  opposed  to  the 
empirical  ego  or  subject-object  with  which  psychology  is 
concerned.  The  transcendental  synthesis  of  apperception 
includes  the  secondary  or  psychological  synthesis  (the 
empirical  self)  as  it  does  the  whole  world  of  experience. 
From  the  synthesis  of  apperception,  the  primordial  "  I 
think,"  every  other  synthesis  is  deducible.  In  so  far  as 
it  refers  to  the  categories  and  their  conditions  which  we 
have  just  been  considering,  it  is  the  *'  pure  Understanding  " 
which  creates  them. 

Having  now  arrived  at  the  fundamental  and  general 
grounds  of  the  distinction  between  propositions  which  are 
necessary  and  universal,  and  such  as  are  contingent  and 
singular,  it  remains  to  deal  with  their  application  to 
phenomena.  We  have  now  clearl}^  distinguished  between 
the  world  of  sense  as  such  and  its  ordered  connection, 
which  we  term  Nature.  Furthermore,  we  have  seen  that 
the  distinction  does  not  lie  in  that  the  one  resides  more, 
the  other  less  in  our  consciousness,  but  that  both  elements 
constituting  real  experience,  the  world  of  mere  sense- 
impressions,  no  less  than  the  same  world  as  modified  by 
Understanding,  is  in  the  one  case  a  series,  and  in  the  other 
a  system,  of  determinations  of  a  conscious  subject  possible  or 
actual.  Kant,  after  repeatedly  assuring  us  that  this  alone 
is  our  world,  proceeds  somewhat  inconsequently  to  postu- 
late a  world  of  things  in  themselves  outside  this  system 
or  world  of  experience.  With  this,  however,  we  are  not 
at  present  concerned. 

Just  as  the  laws  determining  intuition  of  phenomena  as 
sense-presentations,  reside  in  the  Sensibility  itself  and 
constitute  pure  mathematics^  so  the  laws  which  regulate 


238  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

the  co-ordination  of  phenomena  must  be  sought  for  in  the 
Understanding  and  constitute  Pure  natural  science. 

The  transcendental  Analytic  falls  into  two  parts; 
analytic  of  conceptions,  which  is  the  statement  of  the 
ultimate  forms  to  which  unification  may  be  reduced,  and 
analytic  of  principles,  which  exhibits  these  elements  of 
unification,  as  syntheses  in  the  concrete  world  itself.  In 
this  way  the  question,  "  How  are  synthetic  propositions 
a  priori  possible  ?"  is  answered  generally  so  far  as  natural 
science  is  concerned. 

But  although  it  has  been  shown  how  the  universal 
axioms  of  experience  and  of  science  are  possible  in 
general,  it  remains  yet  to  consider  more  nearly  the  manner 
in  which  the  sense-material  is  subsumed  under  the  pure 
conceptions  of  the  Understanding.  This  is  the  problem 
of  those  sections  of  the  '  Critique  '  which  are  occupied  with 
the  schematism  of  the  pure  conceptions  of  the  under- 
standing. The  mediator  between  the  radicall}^  disparate 
elements  of  sense  and  intellect  is  the  pure  form  of  time. 
This,  in  the  words  of  Kant,  "  is  the  third  thing,  which 
on  the  one  side  is  homogeneous  with  the  category,  and 
with  the  phenomenon  on  the  other,  and  so  makes  the 
application  of  the  former  to  the  latter  possible."  "  This 
mediating  representation,"  he  continues,  "  must  be  pure 
(without  any  empirical  content),  and  yet  must,  on  the  one 
side,  be  intellectual,  on  the  other  sensuous."  But  time  is 
at  once  sensuous  and  pure,  and,  therefore,  answers  this 
condition.  The  immediate  form  of  the  category  as  applied 
to  the  sense- world  must,  therefore,  be  one  in  which  it  is 
united  with  time,  or  reduced  to  a  time-determination. 
This  form  is  what  Kant  calls  the  schema,  which  gives  us 
the  category  as  susceptible  of  direct  application  to  the 
phenomenon. 

As  the  Sensibility  is  the  faculty  which  furnishes  the 
sensuous-material  of  knowledge,  the  Understanding  that 
which  creates  the  categories,  so  it  is  the  productive  ima- 
gination which  produces  the  schema,  whose  function  it 
is  to  determine  time  and  space  by  means  of  the  cate- 
gories. There  is  naturally  a  parallelism  between  the 
categories  and  the  schemata.  For  the  categories  of 
Quantity  the  schema  is  number,  which  we  have  already 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  239 

seen  to  be  a  time-determination ;  for  those  of  Relation 
the  schema  is  the  time-determinations — change  and  con- 
timiance,  succession,  simultaneity  ;  for  those  of  modality  the 
time-determinations — sometime,  noio,  always.  All  this  is 
plain-sailing  enough,  but  the  category  of  Quality  offers 
a  little  difficulty.  The  empirical  element  of  feeling  has 
here  to  be  introduced,  and  the  category  of  Quality  can 
only  be  schematised  as  that  of  filled,  filling,  and  empty 
time.  "Between  reality  (presentation  of  feeling)  and 
zero,  i.e.  the  complete  emptiness  of  intuition  in  time, 
there  is  a  difference  which  has  a  quantit3\  For  between 
each  given  degree  of  light  and  darkness,  between  each 
degree  of  heat  and  complete  coldness,  each  degree  of 
weight  and  of  absolute  lightness,  each  degree  of  the 
containing  of  space  and  of  totally  empty  space,  pro- 
gressively smaller  degrees  can  be  thought  of,  and 
similarly  between  consciousness  and  complete  unconscious- 
ness (psychological  darkness)  continually  smaller  [degrees] 
exist.  Hence  no  perception  is  possible  that  would  prove 
an  absolute  void ;  for  instance,  no  psychological  darkness 
that  could  be  viewed  otherwise  than  as  a  consciousness, 
which  is  but  surpassed  by  another  strongei-  consciousness, 
and  the  same  in  all  cases  of  feeling."  (Kant's  '  Prolego- 
mena,' §  24,  Bohn's  edition.)  This  Kant  calls  the  second 
application  of  mathematics  to  natural  science  (matliesis  in- 
tensorum)  ;  the  first,  of  course,  being  the  original  schema  of 
number  {matliesis  extensorum).  The  schemata  of  Eolation 
and  Modality,  which,  like  the  corresponding  categories,  are 
of  course  dynamic,  are  always  subordinate  to  those  of  Quality 
and  Quantity,  which  are  mathematic.  To  the  schemata 
naturally,  as  to  every  other  stage  in  the  construction  of 
experience,  the  synthetic  unity  of  apperception,  the  ever- 
present  "  I  think,"  is  the  ultimate  motive  power. 

These  a  priori  categorised  time-determinations  may  be 
summarised  as  representing  the  time-series,  the  time-con- 
tent, the  time-order,  and  the  time-complex.  They  seve- 
rally furnish  us  with  the  metaphysical  principles  of  science. 
The  schema  of  number  or  of  the  time-series  gives  us  the 
axioms  of  intuition  or  perception,  which  express  in  a  general 
principle  the  fact  that  an  object  of  perception  is  always 
an   aggregate   of    parts,   an   extensive    magnitude ;    the 


240  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

anticipations  of  perception  supply  the  r.'iile  for  the  fact  that 
every  sensation,  feeling  or  conscious  state,  though  it  have 
no  ea;tensive  magnitude,  has  nevertheless  mtensive  magni- 
tude or  degree  (qumititas  qualitatis  est  gradiis) ;  in  other 
words,  both  these  principles  are  based  on  number ;  in  the 
one  case  it  is  a  number  of  parts  outside  one  another,  or 
time-senes,  in  the  other,  a  number  of  successive,  and  there- 
fore anticipatory,  gradations  of  feeling  or  time-content. 
The  principles  corresponding  to  the  schemata  of  Eolation, 
viz.  change  and  continuance,  succession,  and  simultaneity, 
and  which  fix  the  iimQ-order  of  the  phenomenon,  Kant  calls 
analogies  of  experience.  Thej^  are,  that  the  quantity  of 
material  substance  in  the  universe  is  unchangeable ;  that 
every  change  has  an  external  cause,  and  that  in  the  com- 
munication of  motion,  action  and  reaction  must  always 
be  reciprocal.  Finally,  the  three  postulates  of  empirical 
thought  in  general,  based  on  the  categories  of  Modality, 
give  us  the  rules  for  the  physically  possible,  actual,  and 
necessary,  or  in  other  words,  of  the  time-complex. 

These  principles  Kant  insists  are  all  that  a  metaphysic  of 
nature  can  furnish  us  with  a  priori ;  the  rest  must  be  left 
to  observation  and  experiment,  according  to  the  method  of 
induction.*  There  follows  on  this  a  long  section  on  the 
division  of  all  things  into  "  phenomena  and  nomena,"  in 
which  Kant  develops  at  length  his  distinction  between 
the  "  thiug-in-itself  "  and  the  appearance  or  phenomenon 
in  consciousness — between  sensible  and  intelligible  being. 
The  appendix  to  this  section  on  the  "Amphiboly  of  the 
concejDtions  of  reflection,"  deals  with  the  subject  of  the 
confusion  of  the  empirical  use  of  the  Understanding  with 
the  transcendental.  To  this  confusion  Kant  traces  much  of 
dogmatic  metaphysics,  notably  the  doctrines  of  Leibnitz. 
At  the  close  of  the  Transcendental  Analytic,  Kant,  in  the 
second  edition  of  the  '  Critique,'  aj^pends  a  dissertation  on 
the  relation  of  criticism  to  the  empirical  and  dogmatic 
idealistic  theories  of  Berkeley  and  Leibnitz  which  need 
not  detain  us. 

*  For  a  full  development  of  these  fundamental  principles  in  their 
relation  to  matter  and  motion,  the  reader  is  referred  to  my  translation 
of  Kant's  '  Metaphysical  Foundations  of  Natural  Science,'  in  Bohn's 
Philosophical  Library. 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  241 

We  have  now  reached  the  conclusion  of  the  con- 
structive or  constitutive  portion  of  Kant's  Philosophy,  that 
is,  the  portion  in  which  he  seeks  to  lay  before  us  what  goes 
to  the  making  of  experience,  the  data  or  principles  which 
completed  or  real  experience  presupposes.  The  question, 
How  is  experience  possible  ?  is  now  for  Kant  fully  solved. 
But  how  about  the  problems  with  which  dogmatic  meta- 
physics had  hitherto  been  concerned,  which  had  exercised 
the  genius  of  a  Leibnitz  and  the  talent  of  a  Wolff;  which 
were  so  essential  to  morality  and  political  stability ; 
questions  as  to  the  first  cause,  the  immortality  of  the  soul, 
freewill,  &c.  Up  to  this  point  the  tendency  of"  Criticism  " 
had  been  unmistakably  to  show  the  utter  absurdity  of  all 
such  inquiries.  In  the  next  portion  of  the  '  Critique ' 
the  "  Transcendental  Dialectic,"  which  Kant  distinguishes 
from  the  first  part,  by  affirming  it  to  deal  with  regulative 
rather  than  constitutive  conceptions,  be  proceeds  to  treat  of 
these  problems  in  his  own  fashion,  first  "  critically,"  and 
afterwards  "  practically." 


Transcendental  Dialectic. 

This  third  division  of  the  '  Critique '  discusses  the  ques- 
tion :  How  metaphj'sics  in  the  dogmatic  sense  is  possible  ? 
just  as  the  two  previous  divisions  had  discussed  the 
question  :  How  is  experience  possible  ?  We  are  here  con- 
cerned with  the  Pure  Reason,  properly  so  called,  as  we 
have  before  been  dealing  with  the  Pure  Understanding 
and  Pure  Sensibility.  The  two  latter  were  the  faculties 
of  Perceptions  and  of  Conceptions  respectively ;  the 
Reason  is  the  faculty  of  Ideas.  By  "Ideas  "  Kant  under- 
stands those  conceptions  which,  though  they  do  not  enter 
into  the  constitution  of  experience  like  the  categories,  are 
nevertheless,  according  to  Kant,  universally  present  in 
human  consciousness  as  "practical"  or  "regulative" 
principles,  in  the  shape  of  problems,  postulates  and  re- 
quirements. Just  as  the  material  upon  which  the  under- 
standing exercises  itself  is  Sensibility,  so  the  material 
upon  which  the  Reason  operates  is  the  reality  or  experience, 
constituted  by  the  combination  of  the  two  former  elements. 


242  MODEKN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

For  tHis  reason  the  Ideas  transcend  alike  sense-forms  and 
categories,  while,  at  the  same  time,  they  have  a  determi- 
nation entirely  ditFerent  from  either  of  them.  The  former 
are  constitutive  of  experience  itself;  the  latter,  on  the 
other  hand,  are  merely  speculative,  beintr  concerned  with 
problems  which  experience  indeed  suggests  but  which  do 
not  affect  its  constitution,  and  which  its  nature  precludes 
it  from  solving. 

The  distinction  formulated  by  Kant  himself  between 
the  Understanding,  the  logical  function  of  wdiich  is  judg- 
ing, and  the  Eeason,  whose  logical  function  is  syllogising 
(if  I  may  coin  a  word),  is  so  obviously  artificial,  and 
dictated  by  Kant's  love  of  symmetry,  that  it  need  not 
detain  us,  more  especially  as  it  plays  no  important  part  in 
the  subsequent  exposition  of  the  "  Ideas."  Sense  and 
Understanding  are  concerned  with  what  is,  the  Eeason  on 
the  other  hand  with  what  should  be.  Were  we  only  sense 
and  understanding,  we  should  have  no  impulse  to  travel 
beyond  the  region  of  phenomena.  This  faculty  of  Ideas, 
the  Eeason,  forces  us,  however,  beyond  the  conditions  of 
the  given  world  of  experience.  As  the  phenomenon  only 
exists  in  its  relation  to  ourselves  and  to  that  which 
produces  it,  the  sphere  of  experience  is  essentially  the 
sphere  of  the  relative,  the  finite,  and  the  conditioned. 
Now,  all  the  demands  of  the  Eeason  turn  upon  the  search 
for  the  absolute,  the  infinite,  and  the  imconditioned.  The 
great  error  we  are  liable  to  in  the  employment  of  the 
Ideas  of  the  reason,  is  to  forget  or  to  ignore  their  true 
character,  and  to  treat  them  as  constitutive.  The  tempta- 
tion to  this  is  sometimes  great,  and  when  yielded  to  the 
reason  becomes  sophistical  or  dialectical.  Whenever  the 
reason  dogmatises,  that  is,  ventures  assertions  on  matters 
outside  all  possible  experience,  it  falls  into  this  error. 
There  are  cases,  how^e\er,  in  which  such  a  proceeding 
seems  inevitable.  And  in  these  cases  the  sophistications, 
or  dialectic  of  reason,  form  part  of  its  essential  nature,  and 
we  can  no  more  help  our  subjection  to  them  than  we  can 
help  ourselves  being  subject  to  the  illusion  that  the  sun 
moves,  or  that  the  moon  is  larger  wdien  near  the  horizon 
than  at  other  times.  But  just  as  in  the  latter  cases, 
although  the  sense-illusion  itself  does  not  disappear  when 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  243- 

we  know  that  it  is  the  earth  and  not  the  sun  that 
moves,  and  that  the  moon  does  not  vary  in  its  dimensions, 
yet  it  is  nevertheless  rendered  harmless,  inasmuch  as « 
we  cease  to  treat  it  as  reality.  The  same  with  the  illii 
sions  of  the  reason.  As  soon  as  criticism  has  unmasked 
their  true  character,  philosophy  must  cease  to  rely  upon 
them. 

The  Ideas  of  the  Pure  Eeason  embrace  the  Paralogisms, 
the  Antinomies  and  the  Ideal  of  Pure  Eeason.  The  first 
concern  the  absolute  nature  of  the  soul,  the  second  the 
absolute  constitution  of  the  world-order,  and  the  third  the 
absolute  existence  of  God.  The  paralogisms  are  so  called 
because  in  them  it  is  sought  to  show  that  the  soul  is 
simple  and  therefore  immortal ;  that  it  is  substance ; 
that  it  is  distinct  from  the  body;  all  which  propositions 
are  based  on  so  many  ]3aralogisms.  In  his  treatment  of 
this  subject  Kant  first  deals  with  the  arguments  of  Men  - 
delssohn  and  of  Eeimarus,  and,  it  may  be  added,  that  of 
his  teacher  Knutzen,  all  of  whom  emphasised  the  unity  of 
the  self-consciousness  as  the  ground  of  proof  of  the  soul's 
immateriality  and  immortality.  The  paralogism  here 
rests  on  the  fact  that  by  means  of  the  Idea  of  the  uncon- 
ditioned, the  reason  demands  that  the  ego  shall  always 
occupy  the  place  of  subject  and  never  that  of  predicate ; 
that  all  its  presentations  shall  be  referred  to  its  own 
unity ;  and  finally,  that  all  which  it  perceives  shall  be 
regarded  as  other  than,  and  external  to,  itself.  It  is 
sought  to  change  these  valid  requirements,  which  are  all 
fulfilled  in  experience,  into  dogmatic  assertions  respecting 
the  nature  of  the  soul  apart  from  experience. 

The  confusion  at  the  basis  of  this,  as  of  the  other  para- 
logisms, consists  in  the  failure  to  distinguish  between  the 
ego  of  the  ])rimordial  apperception  which,  inasmuch  as  it 
is  that  which  renders  experience  itself  possible,  can  never 
become  an  object  of  experience,  with  the  sonl,  that  is,  the 
object  of  the  internal  sense  (as  Kant  terms  it),  or  in  other 
words,  the  individual  mind  or  personality.  This  latter  is 
as  Hnme  had  shown,  given  us  as  a  series  of  "  impressions 
and  ideas,"  but,  as  Kant  added,  knit  together  and  realised 
under  the  categor}"  of  "substance  "  and  the  schema  of  "  per- 
manence."   This  confusion  is  the  parent  of  other  fallacies  ; 

E  2 


244  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

thus  out  of  the  logical  unity  of  the  subject  is  constituted 
a  real  simplicity ;  from  the  fact  that  I  am  for  myself 
.identical  in  every  moment  of  consciousness,  it  is  concluded 
that  the  soul  is  objectively  an  identical  personality ;  lastly, 
from  the  distinction  between  the  internal  and  external 
sense  and  its  object,  the  subsistence  of  the  soul  independently 
of  the  body  is  inferred.  "  From  all  this  it  is  evident,'* 
says  Kant,  "  that  rational  psychology  has  its  origin  in 
mere  misunderstanding.  The  unity  of  consciousness, 
which  lies  at  the  basis  of  the  categories,  is  considered  to 
be  an  intuition  of  the  subject  as  an  object;  and  the 
category  of  substance  is  applied  to  the  intuition.  But 
this  unity  is  nothing  more  than  the  unity  in  thought,  by 
which  no  object  is  given  ;  to  which,  therefore,  the  category 
of  substance  (which  always  presupposes  a  given  intuition) 
cannot  be  a]:)plied."  Consequently,  the  subject  cannot  be 
cognized.  "  The  subject  of  the  categories  cannot,  therefore, 
for  the  very  reason  that  it  cogitates  these,  frame  any 
conception  of  itself  as  an  object  of  the  categories ;  for,  to 
cogitate  these,  it  must  lay  at  the  foundation  its  own  pure 
self-consciousness  (the  verj'  thing  that  it  wishes  to  explain 
and  describe).  In  like  manner,  the  subject,  in  which 
the  representation  of  time  has  its  basis,  cannot  determine, 
for  this  very  reason,  its  own  existence  in  time.  Now,  if 
the  latter  is  impossible,  the  former,  as  an  attempt  to 
determine  itself  by  means  of  the  categories  as  a  thinking 
beiu!^  in  general,  is  no  less  so."  ('  Critique,'  Bohn's 
edition,  p.  249.) 

The  sum  of  Kant's  investigations  into  the  paralogisms 
of  the  Pure  Eeason  is  that  every  "  rational  psychology  " 
which  claims  to  be  dogmatic,  that  is,  to  establish  doctrines 
concerning  the  real  nature  of  the  soul,  rather  than  to  be 
critical  or  determinative  of  our  attitude  towards  the 
question,  is,  and  must  be,  a  delusion  and  a  snare. 

The  criticism  of  Cosmology  consists  in  the  discussion  of 
the  antinomies  of  the  pure  reason.  The  Idea  of  the  uncon- 
ditioned requires  us  to  expect  a  completed  system  of  all 
phenomena,  or  in  other  words,  a  world.  This  world-Idea 
is  determined  according  to  the  four  classes  of  categories, 
and  may  thus  be  split  up  into  eight  propositions,  consist- 
ing  on   the   one   side  of  the  asseilions  of  the  Wolffian 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  245 

cosmology,  and  on  the  other,  of  their  sceptical  antitheses. 
They  are  as  follows  : — 

TJiesis.  Antithesis. 

The    world     has    a    beginning  The  world  is   infinite  in   time 

(boundary)  in  time  and  space.  and  space. 

Thesis.  Antithesis. 

Everything  in  the  world  con-  There  is  nothing  simple,  but 

sists  of  simple  (parts).  everything  is  composite. 

Thesis.  Antithesis. 

There  are  in  the  world  causes,  There  is  no  freedom,  but  all  is 

through  Freedom.  Nature. 

Tliesis.  Antithesis. 

In  the  series  of  world  causes.  There  is  nothing  necessary,  bu\. 

there  exists  a  necessary  being.  in  this  series  all  is  contingent 

According  to  Kant,  the  natural  dialectic  of  the  Pure 
Reason  is  exhibited  in  these  propositions ;  for,  while  th« 
theses  are  grounded  on  universally  admitted  axioms,  tlie 
antitheses,  which  are  equally  well  accredited,  directly 
contradict  them.  Each  of  the  eight  propositions  is  thus  a 
correct  consequence  from  self-evident  premises.  The  in- 
herent contradiction  is  thereby  shown  to  lie  in  the  nature 
of  the  reason  itself.  For  of  two  mutually  contradictory 
propositions  both  cannot  be  false  unless  the  conception  at 
their  basis  be  itself  contradictory.  Kant's  Transcendental 
or  Critical  Idealism,  which  distinguishes  between  pheno- 
mena and  things -in -them  selves,  and  rescues  the  word 
"  phenomenon "  from  its  sceptical  implication  of  "  illu- 
sion," is  the  sword  which  is  to  cut  this  Gordian  knot. 
The  two  first  antinomies  (the  mathematical)  are  disposed 
of  by  a  demonstration  of  the  fallacy  alike  of  thesis  and 
antithesis,  inasmuch  as  jphenomena  are  here  treated  as 
things-in-themselves.  It  is  just  as  impossible  to  say  the 
world  is  infinite  as  it  is  finite,  for  neither  of  these  concep- 
tions can  be  contained  in  experience,  "  because  experience 
is  neither  possible  respecting  an  infinite  space,  or  an 
infinite  time,  or  the  boundary  of  the  world  by  an  empty 
space  or  a  previous  empty  time ;  these  things  are  only 
Ideas."  On  the  other  hand,  since  both  conceptions  pertain 
to  the  forms  of  sense,  it  would  be  manifestly  absurd  to 


246  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

predicate  eitlier  of  them  of  the  world  as  thing-in-itself. 
The  same  reasoning  applies  to  the  second  antinomy  which 
concerns  the  division  of  phenomena.  For  here  again  the 
parts  only  exist  as  given,  that  is,  in  the  act  of  division,  in 
other  words,  in  experience,  and  hence  only  extend  as  far 
as  experience  reaches.  But  it  is  no  less  impossible  for 
experience  to  dogmatically  fix  a  limit  to  the  division  of 
phenomena  than  it  is  for  it  to  follow  out  that  division  to 
infinity. 

The  two  second  antinomial  pairs  are  not  like  the  first, 
mathematical,  that  is,  concerned  with  the  quantum  of  the 
world,  but  like  their  corresponding  classes  of  categories, 
dynamical,  that  is,  concerned  with  a  determination  of  the 
world-order  in  a  special  manner.  "  In  the  first  class  of 
antinomy  (the  matliematical),  the  fallacy  of  the  assump- 
tion consisted  in  that  what  is  self-contradictoiy  (namely, 
phenomenon  and  thing-in-itself),  was  represented  as 
capable  of  union  in  one  idea.  But  as  regards  the  second, 
or  dynamical  class  of  antinomy,  the  fallacy  of  the  as- 
sumption consists  in  that  what  is  capable  of  union  is 
represented  as  contradictory,  and  consequently,  as  in  the 
first  case,  both  contradictory  assertions  were  false;  so 
here,  where  they  are  opposed  to  one  another  merely 
through  misunderstanding,  both  may  be  true."  (Kanx's 
*  Prolegomena,'  Bohn's  edition,  §  53.) 

In  this  no  less  than  in  the  previous  instance,  it  is  the 
distinction  between  phenomena  and  thiugs-in-themselves 
which  solves  the  difficulty,  though  in  another  way.  Both 
propositions  may  here  be  true,  if  the  thesis  be  referred  to 
things-in-themselves,  and  the  antithesis  to  phenomena. 
It  is  quite  conceivable  that,  while  in  the  phenomenal 
world  all  the  actions  of  man  are  the  necessary  con- 
sequences of  his  empirical  character,  outside  this  phe- 
nomenal world  in  his  capacity  of  thing-in-itself,  existing 
out  of  time,  man  may  be  the  self-determining  cause  of  his 
actions.  It  is  thus  that  Kant  reconciles  liberty  with 
necessity.  Similarly  with  the  fourth  antinomy,  it  may 
be  quite  correct  according  to  the  assumption  of  the  anti- 
thesis, that,  as  in  the  world  of  phenomena,  every  event  has 
a  cause — the  regressus  no  less  than  the  ])rogressus  of  causes 
being  infinite — the  idea  of  a  first  or  uncaused  cause  is 


Erocii  IL]  KANT.  247 

absurd,  inasmuch  as  this  could  only  be  discoverable  could 
we  arrive  at  the  completion  of  the  series  of  suboidinate 
causes,  which  is  obviously  impossible ;  and  nevertheless, 
the  thesis  may  still  obtain  outside  phenomena,  i.e.  outside 
the  world  of  experience,  in  that  of  things-in-themselves. 
There  is  nothing  contradictory  here  in  the  assumption  of 
a  self-existent,  necessary  being,  for  although  the  existence 
of  such  a  being  can  never  be  proved,  yet  it  can  be  just  as 
little  disproved,  time  and  causality  only  applying  to  the 
phenomena  of  sense,  and  not  to  things-in-themselves. 

The  criticism  of  rational  Theology  is  contained  in  the 
section  of  the  '  Critique  '  on  the  Ideal  of  the  Pure  Keason. 
Kant  has  already  led  up  to  it  in  his  discussion  on  the 
■fourth  antinomy.  In  the  Ideal  of  the  Pure  Benson  the 
Idea  of  the  Unconditioned  claims  to  be  presented  in 
individuo  but  not  in  concreto,  being  determined  by  itself 
alone.  "  The  idea  of  humanity  in  its  complete  joerfection 
supposes  not  only  the  advancement  of  all  the  powers  and 
faculties,  which  constitute  our  conception  of  human 
nature,  to  a  complete  attainment  of  their  hnal  aims,  but 
also  everything  which  is  requisite  for  the  complete  deter- 
mination of  the  idea  ;  for  of  all  contradictory  predicates, 
only  one  can  conform  with  the  idea  of  the  perfect  man. 
What  I  have  termed  an  ideal,  was  in  Plato's  philosophy, 
an  idea  of  the  divine  mind — an  individual  object  present 
to  its  pure  intuition,  the  most  perfect  of  every  kind  of 
beings,  and  the  archetype  of  all  phenomenal  existences." 
Q  Critique,'  Bohn's  edition,  pp.  350-1.) 

This  idea  of  the  sum-total  of  all  perfection,  and  of  all 
reality,  conceived  as  concentrated  in  an  individual  being, 
constitutes  the  idea  of  God,  or  the  Ideal  of  the  Pure  Eeason. 
Kant  describes  the  progress  of  the  reason  in  proceeding 
first  to  the  hypostasisation,  and  finally,  to  the  personifica- 
tion of  this  conception  of  a  sum-total  of  all  reality;  but 
that  the  reason  itself  has  a  lurking  suspicion  that  in  the 
course  of  this  procedure  it  has  broken  altogether  with 
experience,  is  shown  by  the  desperate  attempt  to  justify 
itself  exhibited  in  the  three  arguments  (the  ontological,  the 
cosmological  and  the  teleological),  which  it  puts  forward 
in  proof  of  the  objective  existence  of  its  ideal.  Kant 
proceeds  to  show  the  illusoriness  of  all  these  arguments. 


248  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

But  if  all  the  pretended  proofs  of  the  existence  of  the 
Deity  are  based  on  illusions  of  the  Pure  Eeason,  the 
atheistic  demonstrations  of  the  opposite  are  equally 
baseless,  on  the  other  hand.  The  non-existence  of  God 
can  just  as  little  be  demonstrated  as  his  existence.* 

"  The  reason  does  not  here,"  observes  Kant,  (with  refer- 
ence to  this  third  or  Theological  Idea)  "  as  with  the  pyscho- 
logical  and  cosmological  ideas,  start  from  experience,  and  is 
not  by  a  [progressive]  raising  (Steigerung)  of  the  grounds, 
misled  into  an  endeavour  to  contemplate  the  series  in 
absolute  completeness,  but  wholly  breaks  therewith,  and 
from  mere  conceptions  of  what  would  constitute  the 
absolute  completeness  of  a  thing-in- general,  consequently 
by  means  of  the  idea  of  a  most  perfect  original  being, 
descends  to  the  determination  of  the  possibility,  and 
thereby  also  to  the  reality,  of  all  other  things."  (Kant's 
'  Prolegomena,'  Bohn's  edition,  §  55.)  Thus  much  as  to 
the  form  in  which  the  Ideal  is  conceived.  As  regards  its 
content,  its  real  purport  and  meaning,  it  is  an  indis- 
pensable regulative  conception  for  our  study  of  nature, 
no  less  than  for  our  conduct ;  that  is,  the  reason  requires 
that  we  regard  nature  as  though  created  and  governed  by 
God,  and  that  we  act  as  though  we  were  accountable  to 
God.  The  regulative,  or  disciplinary  function  of  the  Pure 
Eeason  as  regards  scientific  method,  and  the  systematisa- 
tion  of  knowledge,  is  developed  in  the  closing  sections  of 
the '  Critique,'  which  treat  of  the  "  Transcendental  doctrine 
of  method." 

Kant's  practical  or  moral  philosophy  is  contained  most 
fully  in  '  The  Metaphysic  of  Ethics,'  and  in  the  '  Critique 
of  Practical  Reason.'  The  basis  of  Kant's  Ethic  is  the 
"  categorical  imperative  "  by  which  the  Practical  Eeason 
affirms  its  domination  over  the  natural  impulses.  'Ihe 
moral  man  is,  according  to  Kant,  not  he  who  is  by  nature 
benevolent,  but  he  who  acts  well  against  his  natural 
inclinations.      The   great   distinction   of  Transcendental 

*  From  Kant's  "  practical "  standpoint,  this  fact  has  an  important 
bearing,  and  therefore  the  stress  he  lays  upon  it  is  ju.-tified.  Not  so 
with  mir  modern  Positivists,  Agnostics,  and  others  with  whom  it  is 
no  more  than  a  verbal  quibble,  and  whose  repudiation  of  Atheism  can 
but  denote  mere  social  servility. 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  249 

Idealism  between  noumenon  or  thing-in-itself  and  phenomenon 
or  appearance  in  consciousness,  of  course  plays  an  even 
more  important  role  here  than  in  the  theoretical  side  of 
the  critical  philoso{>hy.  Man's  will,  as  noumenon,  proclaims 
the  moral  law  which  man's  will,  as  phenomenon,  receives. 
The  categorical  imperative,  the  "  ought  of  that  which  has 
never  happened,"  as  Kant  expresses  it,  can  only  have  a 
meaning  for  me  in  so  far  as  I  feel  within  me  the  possibility 
of  my  accomplishing  the  demand  made  upon  me.  The 
fact  that  it  does  appeal  to  me  affords  all  the  proof  requisite 
for  me  that  the  will  is  free.  Inasmuch  as  without  free- 
dom no  ought  or  moral  law  is  conceivable,  the  latter  is  itself 
as  much  a  demonstration  of  the  former  as  the  former  is  the 
foundation  of  the  latter.  The  conviction  of  this  moral  free- 
dom must,  however,  in  no  way  be  conceived  as  extending 
our  theoretical  knowledge.  It  simply  affords  a  subjective 
demonstration  of  what  the  Transcendental  Dialectic  had 
already  declared  possible,  though  incapable  of  any  positive 
theoretical  proof.  We  have  at  the  same  time  a  subjective 
confirmation  of  another  fact,  which  the  I'ranscendental 
Dialectic  had  proclaimed  conceivable,  though  not  demon- 
strable, namely,  that  of  our  dual  nature.  While  we  are 
sensuous  beings  in  time,  we  are  intelligible  beings  apart 
from  time.  It  is  in  my  noumenal,  intelligible,  or  which 
is  the  same  thing,  my  moral  nature,  that  I  am  really  free, 
this  freedom  consisting  in  the  power  of  the  unconditioned 
commencement  of  a  series  of  events  in  time.  Thus 
practical  necessity  compels  us  to  make  assumptions  which 
would  be  unwarranted  were  we  to  confine  ourselves  to 
the  theoretical  aspect  of  the  case.  In  this  we  see  the 
superiority  of  the  Practical  over  the  Pure  Reason.  These 
assumptions  are  the  postulates  of  the  Practical  Reason  by 
which  we  are  to  understand  its  necessary  presuppositions 
for  practical  purposes,  but  which  have  no  theoretical  or 
speculative  bearing  whatever.  In  this  connection,  Kant 
steadily  adheres  to  his  original  contention  that  a  man  is 
no  more  able  to  increase  his  knowledge  by  meie  concep- 
tions, than  a  merchant  is  to  increase  his  riches  by  adding 
noughts  to  the  balance  of  his  account. 

It  will  be  seen  from  the  foregoing  that  Kant's  basis  of 
Ethics  is  absolute  intuition.     The  dictates  of  conscience 


250  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

are  ultimate,  and  not  traceable  to  any  higher  external 
source.  Kant  polemicises  against  the  moral  philosophy 
which  places  the  principle  of  the  action  in  the  object 
desired,  snch  as  happiness,  perfection,  &c.  It  is  cjuite 
evident  that  that  is  desired  which  affords  pleasure,  but 
this  is  obviously  only  an  empirical  principle.  Even  the 
principle  of  perfection  is  open  to  the  criticism  that  it  only 
puts  forward  conditional  demands,  and  consequently 
affords  no  adequate  distinction  between  expediency  and 
morality.  This  objection  is  obviated,  once  we  place  the 
criterion  of  morality  in  the  commands  of  the  Practical 
Eeason,  and  recognise  them  as  ultimate,  and  per  se  of 
universal  validity.  The  formula  of  this  universal  princi- 
ple may  be  thus  stated :  so  act  that  the  maxims  of  your 
conduct  may  serve  as  a  rule  valid  for  all. 

The  conformit}'  of  the  action  with  the  above  formula 
constitutes  the  conduct  legal,  the  conformity  of  the  motive 
makes  it  moral.  The  metaphysic  of  Ethics  may  be  divided 
accordingly  into  the  doctrine  of  right  (jurisprudence) 
and  the  doctrine  of  virtue  (Ethics  proper).  The  first 
comprises  the  external  and  legally  binding  ;  the  second,  the 
duties  with  which  conscience  is  concerned.  The  one  is 
treated  of  in  Kant's  "  Theory  of  Jurisprudence  "  the  other 
in  his  "  Theory  of  Virtue." 

Kant's  views  on  the  philosophy  of  history,  the  conception 
of  which  was  at  that  time  recent,  are  contained  in  a  re- 
markable little  essay  entitled,  "  Ideas  for  a  Universal 
History  from  a  Mundane  Point  of  View."  Kant  here  enun- 
ciates the  now  familiar  <but  then  novel  conception  that 
"  individuals  and  even  entire  peoples,  little  imagine  that  in 
following  their  own  interest,  and  often  in  struggling  with 
one  another,  they  pursue  each  in  their  own  way,  as  a 
conducting  filament,  the  design  of  nature,  to  them  un- 
known, and  co-operate  in  an  evolution  which,  even  if  they 
had  an  idea  of  it,  would  signify  little  for  them."  And 
again,  "  there  remains  but  one  issue  for  the  philosopher, 
and  that  is,  it  being  impossible  for  him  to  suppose  in  the 
play  of  the  actions  of  men  a  reasonable  design  of  theii 
own,  he  must  endeavour  to  discover  in  the  apparently 
absurd  eon«atenations  of  human  affairs,  a  natural  design 
which  renders  it  possible  to  trace  among  creatures,   who 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  251 

themselves  proceed  without  plan,  a  history  conformable  to 
a  plan  determined  by  nature."  The  following  are  the 
principal  points  in  the  little  brochure  from  the  introduction 
to  which  the  above  passages  are  taken.  Kant  admits  a 
continuous  development,  subject  to  constant  laws,  in 
human  history.  The  aspirations,  the  struggles,  and  the 
work,  of  one  generation,  bear  fruit  and  are  realised 
in  the  next,  only  to  become  in  their  turn  the  material 
for  further  development.  This  conception  gives  to  the 
present  a  real  bond  of  union  with  the  past  and  the  future. 
The  primitive  savage  condition,  to  a  large  ejj:tent  abolished 
in  the  relations  between  individual  men,  still  exists  in  the 
relations  of  states  to  one  another.  This  can  onl}'  be 
terminated  by  the  institution  of  an  international  federation 
of  states.  The  solidarity  of  all  the  members  of  the  human 
family,  their  union  in  a  world-republic  in  which  the  dis- 
tinction between  Ethics  and  Politics  would  cease,  and  the 
conscious  end  of  which  would  be  the  well-being  and  pro- 
gress of  humanity  as  a  whole,  such  was  fur  Kant  the  goal 
of  history. 

That  Kant  was  stirred  to  these  thoughts  by  the  spirit 
and  events  of  the  time  (the  essay  was  written  in  1789) 
there  is  no  doubt ;  but  how  different  the  scientific  value 
of  Kant's  contribution  to  the  great  question,  trifling 
though  it  is  in  dimensions ;  how  vastly  deeper  and  more 
comprehensive  his  conception  of  the  true  bearing  of  history, 
than  is  to  be  found  in  any  other  of  the  writings  of  the 
"  age  of  reason ! "  These,  one  and  all,  saw  in  the  past  little, 
if  anything,  more  than  a  seething  mass  of  conscious 
knavery  and  folly,  which  it  was  the  function  of  mature 
human  reason  to  unmask  and  denounce.  Kant  saw  in  it  the 
parent  of  the  present.  He  saw  that  history  is  no  more  ^he 
fortuitous  concatenation  of  knaveries  and  follies  the  men  of 
the  Aufiddrung  declared  it,  than  it  is  the  arbitrary  dispensa- 
tion of  the  suppsrnatural  being  the  theologians  declared  it. 
Of  course  we  find  the  inevitable  shortcomings  of  an  eigh- 
teenth-century view  of  the  subject.  That  political  forms 
are  merely  the  outcome  and  seal,  so  to  speak,  of  the  several 
stages  in  the  social,  and,  more  particularly,  the  economical 
development  of  society,  was  a  truth  not  even  the  most  far- 
seeing  eighteenth-century  thinker  could  be  expected  to 


252  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

grasp.  And  Kant,  of  conrse,  did  not  grasp  it.  With  him, 
as  with  his  contemporaries  generally,  the  political  and 
juridical  aspect  of  hnraan  affairs  was  the  fundamental  one  : 
so  far  as  progress  was  concerned,  their  reconciliation  with 
individual  morality  and  liberty  the  final  statement  of  the 
problem  to  be  resolved. 

On  the  '  Critique  of  the  Faculty  of  Judgment,'  the 
third  of  the  great  critical  treatises  of  Kant,  in  which  he 
formulates  a  theory  of  the  sublime  and  beautiful,  space 
precludes  our  entering.  The  work,  as  before  remarked,  is 
vicjiibly  inferior — look  at  it  from  what  point  of  view  we  may 
— to  its  predecessors.  It  is  needless  to  say  it  is  not  with- 
out happy  and  valuable  suggestions,  but,  taken  all  in  all, 
it  must  be  pronounced  arid,  confused  and  unappreciative. 
Kant's  character  was  especially  deficient  on  the  artistic 
side,  and  it  is  not  surprising  that  his  efforts  to  deal  with 
art,  and  the  emotions  of  which  art  is  the  expression,  should 
have  resulted  in  something  like  a  failure. 

Upon  the  wide  influence  of  Kant  on  y;eneral  culture,  it 
would  carry  us  bej^ond  the  province  of  the  present  volume 
to  dilate.  Well-nigh  every  department  of  learning,  received 
an  impulse  from  the  founder  of  '  The  Critical  Philosophy.' 
The  reception  which  '  Criticism '  met  with  was  un- 
paralleled. "  Many  regarded  Kant,"  says  Yaihinger 
(^Commentar^  pp.  9-10),  "  as  a  prophet  of  a  new  religion, 
and  Keinhold  declared  that  in  an  hundred  years  Kant 
would  have  the  reputation  of  Jesus  Christ.  The  Jena 
Allgemeine  Literatur  Zeitung  proclaimed  a  novus  ordo  rerum. 
In  the  course  of  some  ten' years  three  hundred  attacks  and 
defences  of  Kant's  philosophy  appeared.  The  enthusiasm 
aroused  the  hatred  of  opponents.  Herder  characterised 
the  whole  movement  as  a  St.  Vitus  dance,  while  fanatical 
priests  sought  to  degrade  the  name  of  the  sage  of 
Konigsberg  to  a  dog's  name.  We  must  not  only  be 
acquainted  with  the  books  written  from  a  more  or  less 
impartial  standpoint,  but  also  with  the  subjectively 
coloured  pamphlets  and  letters  belonging  to  the  i^eriod, 
if  we  are  to  form  an  adequate  idea  of  the,  at  present, 
almost  inconceivable  commotion.  The  powerful  im- 
pression of  the  Kantian  philosophy  on  all  classes  in  the 
nation,  implied  a  corresponding  influence  on  every  sphere 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  253 

of  intellectual  activity.  Theology,  jurisprudence,  philo- 
logy, even  natural  science  and  medicine,  were  soon  drawn 
into  the  movement,  quite  apart,  of  course,  from  the  special 
philosophical  disciplines  which  were  subjected  to  its 
mighty  influence." 

The  effect  produced,  however,  was  not  quite  immediate. 
Little  notice  was  taken  of  the  original  "dissertation," 
which  contained  all  the  ideas  of  the  '  Critique '  in  germ, 
while,  as  regards  the  only  important  review  of  the 
*  Critique '  itself,  it  cannot  be  denied  that  it  justified 
Kant's  stricture,  that  the  criticism  had  preceded  the  study 
of  the  work  ciiticised.  Among  the  earliest  and  best 
known  of  the  popular  writers  on  Kantianism  was 
K.  L.  Eeinhold,  who,  in  his  "  Letters  on  the  Kantian 
Philosophy,"  endeavoured  to  show  that  all  the  oppositions 
which  had  hitherto  divided  philosophy  were  disposed  of 
by  the  new  sj'stem.  The  foundation  in  1785  of  the  Jena 
Allgemeine  Literatur  Zeitung  contributed  much  to  its  spread. 
By  the  last  decade  of  the  century  there  was  scarcely  a 
German  university  in  which  the  new  philosophy  was  not 
taught ;  while  its  name  at  least,  and  in  some  cases  more 
than  the  name,  had  spread  far  and  wide  throughout 
western  Europe.  Among  the  men  of  letters  most  power- 
fully influenced  by  Kant,  were,  Frederick  Schiller,  and 
Jean-Paul  Friedrich  Eichter. 

Among  the  most  prominent  opponents  of  the  '  Critical 
Philosophy '  may  be  mentioned  Johann  Gottlieb  Herder. 
Herder  was  at  one  time  a  pupil  of  the  Konigsberg  sage, 
but  was  more  especially  influenced  by  Haraann,  a  friend 
of  Kant,  but  at  the  same  time  an  opponent  of  the  Kantian 
philosophy.  The  subtle  distinctions  of  the  '  Critique '  re- 
pelled Hamann,  who  from  a  Humian-sceptical  attitude  in 
philosophy,  sought  refuge  in  amystical religious  illuminism. 
Herder's  position  was  similar;  like  Hamann,  Herder  lays 
great  sttess  on  language  as  that  which  crucially  differenti- 
ates man  from  the  higher  animals.  But  Herder  none  the  less 
insists  on  the  natural  or  human,  as  opposed  to  the  super- 
natural origin  of  language.  In  the  "  Ideas  for  a  philosophy 
of  histor}'-  "  he  seeks  to  show  that  in  order  to  understand 
the  microcosm,  man,  it  is  necessary  to  understand  the 
universe ;  since  man's  place  in  or  above  nature  is  deter- 


254  MODEEN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II 

mined  by  the  planet  in  which  he  lives,  by  the  geo- 
graphical, topographical,  climatic,  environment  into  which 
he  is  born,  and  finally  by  his  original  organisation.  The 
whole  of  Herder's  thought  is  permeated  by  a  poetical 
pantheism  and  nature  worship  akin  to  the  spirit  of 
the  eighteenth  century,  but  totally  alien  to  that  of 
Kant,  against  whom  Herder  polemicises  with  bitterness 
in  his  ' Metahitik.' 

The  special  representative  in  philosophy  of  the  above 
religio-mystical  opposition  to  Kant,  however,  was  Friedrich 
Heinrich  Jacobi  (1743-1819\  Jacobi,  while  accepting 
Kant's  limitation  of  knowdedge  to  experience,  and  ac- 
knowledging the  invalidity  of  all  reasoning  respecting 
the  unconditioned,  joins  issue  with  him  on  the  matter  of 
the  "  faith  "  which  is  to  rehabilitate  the  dogmas  that  are 
excluded  from  the  province  of  reason.  Kant's  "  jDractical 
necessity  "  will  not  suffice  for  Jacobi.  For  him  certainty 
of  the  existence  of  God,  the  soul,  &c.,  is  afforded  by  an 
immediate  intuition  which  is  itself  ultimate.  The  power- 
lessness  of  reason  with  regard  to  the  question,  is  of  the 
same  nature  as  its  powerlessness  to  prove  or  disprove  an 
immediate  intuition  of  sense,  which  is  also  ultimate.  Of 
the  nature  of  such  an  intuition  is  the  "  faith  "  of  Jacobi. 
Jacobi's  position,  it  may  be  observed,  w^as  but  a  revival  of 
the  stoical  test  of  truth  as  consisting  in  "  strength  of 
individual  conviction,"  and  in  a  modified  form,  of  the  Neo- 
platonic  "  ecstat^y."  At  such  a  point  of  view  philosophy 
necessarily  ceases  to  be  philosoj)hy,  and  becomes  mere 
theosophy  and  mysticism. 

In  the  flood  of  philosophical  literature  which  the  Kantian 
movement  produced,  the  most  prominent  names  beside  that 
of  Eeinhold  above  mentioned,  are  those  of  Schulze,  Fries, 
Beck,  Maimon,  and  Bardili,  all  of  whom  occupied  a  more 
or  less  critical  position  with  regard  to  the  master,  while 
acknowledging  the  fundamental  positions  of  the  new 
philosophy. 

In  attempting  to  discover  a  modus  vivendi  between  the 
Dogmatism  which  professed  to  transcend  experience  and 
the  Empiricism  which  accepted  experience  as  an  ultimate 
fact,  wdthout  further  inquiry  into  its  nature  or  significance, 


Epoch  II.]  KANT.  255 

Kant  struck  upon  the  crucial  distinction  between  elemental 
or  transcendental  and  real  or  empirical  condition.  For 
the  first,  the  self-consistency  of  thought,  necessity  in  the 
order  of  coherence  in  the  given  whole,  is  the  ultimate 
criterion ;  for  the  second,  the  necessary  relation  of  events 
in  time  as  determined  by  causality.  Kant  was  unable  to 
keep  the  distinction  steadily  in  view,  a  circumstance  not  to 
be  wondered  at,  considering  the  difficulties  which  he,  as  a 
pioneer,  had  to  contend  with,  in  striking  out  his  new  "  foot- 
path "  as  he  termed  it.  Many  a  time  does  he  wander  back 
into  the  old  beaten  road  of  Empiricism  or  Dogmatism 
unintentionally,  and  even  without  knowing  it,  when  in 
the  midst  of  following  out  a  transcendental  argument. 
This  is  facilitated  by  his  employing  on  the  one  side  the 
arrangement  and  terminology  of  the  empirical  psycho- 
logists, and  on  the  other  that  of  the  Leibnitz-Wolffiau 
dogmatists.  The  distinctions  of  subject-object,  mind- 
world,  pJienomenon-noumenon,  &c.,  frequently  mislead  him 
as  to  the  real  bearing  of  his  own  thought,  and  make  him 
forget  that  his  point  of  view  properly  transcends  all 
these  distinctions.  The  pedantic  working-out  of  the 
system,  the  forced  symmetry  striven  for  at  every  turn, 
which  has  been  so  often  animadverted  upon,  on  the  other 
hand,  is  largely  to  be  accounted  for  by  the  influence  of  the 
dogmatic  system,  which  he  made  his  model  as  far  as  the 
order  and  arrangement  of  his  exposition  was  concerned. 
The  symmetry  is  sometimes  attained  by  the  most  obvious 
verbal  quibble,  as  for  example,  where  in  order  to  make  a 
perfect  parallel  between  the  ideas  and  the  categories,  a 
laboured  piece  of  augmentation  is  introduced  to  derive  them 
from  the  form  of  the  syllogism,  the  categories  having 
been  derived  from  the  form  of  the  judgment.  Many  other 
instances  will  occur  to  the  reader  versed  in  the  '  Critique.' 
"  Criticism  "  viewed  as  a  system  occupies  a  position  of 
unstable  equilibrium.  Its  professed  solutions,  in  almost 
every  case,  have  the  effect  of  opening  up  deeper  issues. 
There  are  man 3^  things  in  it  that  are  so  plainly  "  survivals  " 
from  the  dogmatic  and  empirical  schools  which  criticism 
professed,  and,  in  the  main  with  justice,  to  have  superseded, 
that  no  student  of  logical  mind,  who  had  once  grasped  the 
central  thought  of  the  new  system,  could  rest  satisfied  with 


256  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

it  as  it  stood.  For  instance,  he  could  hardly  fail  to  see 
that  the  Leibnitz-Lockeian  "  things-in-themselves,"  the 
occult  cause  of  the  sense-impression,  which  were  never- 
theless wholly  outside  that  "  experience  "  for  which  alone, 
as  Kant  had  been  careful  to  demonstrate,  the  conception  of 
cause  and  effect  had  any  meaning  or  significance — were  a 
"  survival  "  certainly  not  of  the  fittest.  But,  after  making 
all  due  detractions,  Kant  remains  the  most  encyclopaedic 
thinker  the  world  had  seen  since  Aristotle,  a  veritable  sun 
in  the  intellectual  firmament.  There  is  no  subject  which 
Kant's  philosophy  did  not  cover,  and  to  which  he  did  not 
himself  apply  it.  But  the  great  heritage  he  left  was  not 
the  "  critical "  system,  but  the  "  critical,"  elemental,  or 
transcendental  method,  the  method  which  was  discovered 
in  principle  by  Kant,  himself  by  no  means  fully  aware  of 
its  wide-reaching  importance,  and  perfected  as  regards 
form  by  Hegel.  This  method,  we  must  once  more  repeat, 
consisted  in  the  reduction  by  analysis  of  a  given  synthesis  to 
its  elementary  constituents  in  order  to  reconstruct  it  in  the  forms 
of  abstract  thought  from  its  jprimary  datum.  This  method  is 
the  method  of  philosophy  par  excellence.  The  thought  of 
Plato  and  of  Aristotle  is  based  upon  it,  but  from  their 
time  to  that  of  Kant  it  had  been  more  or  less  lost  sight  of. 
In  our  next  thinker,  Fichte  we  shall  see  this  "re-reading,"  as 
it  has  been  called,  of  experience,  this  reconstruction  of  the 
concrete  or  real  world  according  to  its  elemental  conditions, 
more  successfully  carried  out  than  by  Kant.  Fichte  found 
the  track  already  cut,  and  it  only  remained  for  him  to 
widen  the  path,  and  to  clear  away  as  far  as  possible  the 
dogmatic  and  empirical  debris  which  still  encumbered  it. 


FICHTE. 

Life. 

JoHANN  GoT-fLiEB  FiCHTE  was  bom.  May  19,  1762,  at 
Eammenau  in  Ober-Lausitz.  He  received  his  higher 
education  at  the  universities  of  Jena  and  Leipzig,  where 
he  entered  in  the  faculty  of  Theology.  For  some  years 
subsequently  he  resided  in  Switzerland  in  the  capacity  of 
private  tutor.     Shortly  after  he  left  Switzerland,  having 


Epoch  II.]  FICHTE.  257 

meanwhile  abandoned  his  intention  of  enterinpf  the  church, 
he  became  acquainted  with  the  new  philosophy  of  which 
the  'Ciitique'  was  the  organon.  His  enthusiasm  knew  no 
bounds,  and  resulted  in  the  production  of  a  work  on 
Kantian  principles,  entitled  a  '  Critique  of  all  Iicvela- 
tion,'  for  which  Kant  procured  him  a  publisher,  and 
which  was  mistaken  by  many  persons  at  first  for  an 
anonymons  work  of  the  master,  so  thoroughly  had  he 
assimilated  the  style,  as  well  as  the  thought  of  the  Titan 
of  Kiinigsberg,  In  Switzerland,  whither  Fichte  again 
repaired  in  order  to  get  manied,  in  1793,  he  published 
anonymously  a  lecture  '  On  the  Claims  of  Free  I'hought,' 
together  with  a  work,  '  Contributions  towards  Kectifying 
the  Public  Judgment  on  the  French  Eevolution,'  in  which 
he  ardently  championed  the  cause  of  the  peo^^le  against 
the  then  governing  classes,  royal,  noble,  and  ecclesiastical. 
These  were  followed  by  some  magazine  articles  on 
Schulze's  '  JSnesidemus '  in  1794.  In  the  same  year, 
Fichte  was  called  to  Jena,  to  succeed  Eeinhold  in  the  Chair 
of  Philosophy.  The  small  hrochure  on  the  '  Conception  of 
Theory  of  Knowdedge,'  which  appeared  soon  after,  contains 
the  programme  of  his  lectures.  This  was  followed  almost 
immediately  by  his  first  great  w^ork,  '  The  Foundation  of 
the  Complete  Theory  of  Knowledge,'  '  Grundlage  der 
gesammten  Wissenscliaftslelire.''  Next  came  '  The  Foundation 
of  Natural  Right  on  the  Principles  of  Theory  of  Know- 
ledge,' in  1796,  and  the  '  Theory  of  Ethics,'  in  1798.  A 
cry  of  atheism  that  was  raised  against  him,  led  to  the 
publication  of  his  appeal  to  the  public  in  1799,  but  he  lost 
his  professorship  at  Jena,  notwithstanding.  Fichte  then 
repaired  to  Berlin,  and  in  a  short  time  obtained  the  Chair 
of  Philosophy  at  Erlangen.  Finally,  in  1809,  he  became 
professor  at  the  Berlin  University,  and  retained  the  post 
till  his  death  on  January  the  27  th,  1814. 

He  published  his  '  Destiny  of  Man  '  and  his'  Close  Com 
mercial  State '  in  1800;  his  ' Sun- clear  Statement '  in  1801; 
his  '  Characteristics  of  the  Present  Age,'  and  'Nature  of  the 
Scholar,'  in  1806;  and  his  'Addresses  to  the  German  Nation,' 
in  1808.  Fichte's  complete  works  have  been  issued  by  his 
son ;  first  the  posthumous  writings  (vols,  iii.,  Bonn,  1834), 
and  subsequently  a   collected  edition  of  the  works  pub- 

s 


258  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

lished  during  the  elder  Fit^hte's  lifetime  (vol.  viii.,  Berlin, 
1845). 


The  Wissenschaftslehre,  or  "  Theory  of  Knowledge." 

Though  Fichte's  system,  to  which  he  gave  the  above 
name,  is  ^^rimarily  based  on  Kant,  it  was  modified  directly 
by  a  study  of  the  exponents  and  critics  of  '  Criiicism,' 
lieinhold,  Schulze  and  Maim.on.  The  influence  upon  it  of 
Fichte's  early  study  of  Spinoza  is  also  not  to  be  overlooked. 
Spinoza's  Monism  had  early  attracted  Fichte,  and  con- 
tributed powerfully  to  mould  his  subsequent  thought. 
Fichte  rightly  signalises  as  the  eiDOch-making  work  of 
Kant,  his  having  directed  philosophy  toward  transcen- 
dental inquiries.  While  other  sciences  investigate  the 
nature  of  known  objects,  it  is  the  function  of  philosophy 
to  discover  the  nature  and  conditions  of  knowledge  itself. 
Philosophy  is  hence  entitled  to  be  called  the  "  science  of 
knowledge,"  and  its  doctrine  *'  theory  of  science,"  jpar 
excellence. 

Inasmuch  as  philoi^ophy  is  occupied  with  knowledge 
alone,  as  its  subject-matter,  the  philosopher  cannot 
recognise  any  substantive  existence  or  thing-in-itself 
outside  knowledge.  Furthermore,  philosophy  which  is 
concerned  not  with  the  content,  but  with  the  conditions 
of  knowledge,  has  no  more  concern  with  the  object  of 
psychology  than  it  has  with  any  empirical  object  of 
external  intuition.  The  task  of  philosophy  is  rather  to 
give  a  transcendental  deduction  of  the  process  of  knowing. 
Scientific  method  demands  that  this  deduction  should 
proceed  from  a  single  fundamental  principle  or  axiom, 
this  fundamental  principle  being  one  which  precedes  the 
distinction  between  speculative  and  practical  that  Kant 
had  formulated.  The  test  of  the  correctness,  nay  of  the 
very  existence,  of  a  "  theory  of  knowledge  "  consists  in  its 
ability,  from  a  fundamental  axiom,  to  deduce  the  subor- 
dinate momenta  or  syntheses  of  consciousness.  Of  course 
since  consciousness  is  the  fact  to  be  explained,  this 
principle  cannot  fall  within  consciousness  as  anyp«r/  of 
its  content.     It  must  not  be  supposed,  however,  for  this 


ErociT  TT.]  FTCHTE.  250 

reason  tliat  "  Tlicorj^  of  Knowledge  "  is  a  mere  fiction  of 
the  imagination :  it  is  rather  the  disclosing  of  the 
mechanism  by  which  empirical  consciousness  comes  to 
pass — a  mechanism  which  cannot  j;er  se  be  object  of  that 
consciousness,  inasmuch  as  it  is  the  conditio  sine  qua  non^ 
which  that  consciousness  presupposes. 

"Theory  of  Knowledge,"  as  science,  must  constitute 
a  system  which  must  contain  implicitly  the  principles 
of  all  other  sciences.  The  fundamental  axiom  on  which 
"  Theory  of  Know^ledge "  rests,  must  be  one  by  which 
the  matter  and  form  of  knoM^ledge  are  alike  conditioned. 
"We  have,"  says  Fichte  {Wtrke,  vol.  i.,  p.  91),  "to 
search  for  the  absolutely  primal  ultimate  and  uncondi- 
tioned principle  of  all  human  knowledge.  As  an  absolutely 
primal  principle  it  does  not  admit  of  demonstration  or  defini- 
tion. It  must  exjorcss  that  deed-action  (^ThatJiandlung) 
which  does  not  and  cannot  appear  among  the  empirical 
determinations  of  our  consciousness,  but  which  rather 
underlies  all  consciousness,  and  alone  makes  it  possible." 
The  primal  act  in  and  through  which  the  unity  of  the 
subjective  and  objective  and  all  other  syntheses  is  given, 
Fichte  finds  in  the  assertion  by  the  ego  of  its  own  being. 
The  form  in  which  he  expounds  this  ground-principle  of 
his  philosophy  is  rather  calculated  to  give  rise  to  the  very 
misconception  against  which  he  guards  his  readers  in  the 
passage  above  quoted,  namely,  that  it  can  be  proved.  He 
connects  it  at  starting,  that  is  to  say,  with  the  logical  law 
of  identity  of  which  the  formula  is  A  =  A.  Fichte's 
only  purpose  in  this,  however,  is  to  convince  the  formal 
logician  with  wdiom  the  above  principle  is  ultimate,  that 
this  very  "  law  of  thought,"  ultimate  as  it  seems,  is  only 
valid  provided  that  A  be  originally  posited ;  in  other 
words,  that  the  law  of  identity  is  only  the  abstract  formula 
of  the  original  act  of  "  self-positing."  The  true  formula 
for  the  latter  is  the  proposidon  lam  I. 

This  first  position  of  Fichte,  as  will  be  seen,  is  identical 
with  the  "  oiiginal  sjmthetic  unity  of  apperception  "  of 
Kant.  "  That  whose  being  (essence)  consists  merely  in  that  it 
posits  itself  as  existent,  says  Fichte,  "  is  the  ego  as  absolute 
subject."  Fichte  wards  off  the  common  confusion  between 
the  Jof  apperception,  the  ego  as  absolute,  universal  subject, 

s  2 


2(50  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

and  the  Me  of  empirical  thought,  the  ego  as  relative,  in- 
dividual object.  "  One  often  hears  the  question  propounded  : 
icltat  was  I  before  I  came  to  self-consciousness  ?  .  .  .  The 
possibility  of  the  above  question  rests  on  a  confusion 
between  the  ego  as  subject,  and  the  ego  as  object  of  the 
reflection  of  the  absolute  subject,  and  is  in  itself  utterly 
inadmissible.  The  ego  forms  the  presentment  of  itself, 
articulates  itself  in  the  form  of  presentation  and  becomes 
something,  an  object;  consciousness  acquires  in  this  way  a 
substratum  which  is  .  .  .  such  a  state  is  postulated,  and 
it  is  asked  what  was  I  then,  i.e.  what  is  the  substratum  of 
consciousness.  But  at  the  very  time  t'uLs  question  is  asked 
the  absolute  subject  is  assumed  as  the  auove  substratum  of 
intuition ;  in  other  words,  that  is  suireptitiously  replaced 
in  thought  of  which  abstraction  was  professed  to  have  been 
made  ;  and  the  question  thus  contradicts  itself.  We  cannot 
think  at  all  without  presupposing  in  thought  the  Ego  as 
conscious  of  itself ;  we  can  never  abstract  from  self-con- 
sciousness, hence  all  questions  of  the  above  kind  are 
unanswerable,  for  they  are,  when  properly  understood,  im- 
possible (^Werlce,  vol.  i.  p.  97). 

From  the  Ego  as  absolute  subject  or  activity  all 
reality  is  deducible.  There  is  no  reality  but  what  is 
translated,  so  to  speak,  by  and  from  the  absolute  subject. 
It  will  be  now  sufficiently  clear  to  tlie  reader  that  by 
the  I,  or  (to  put  it  in  its  latinised  form  to  which  the 
English  reader  is  more  accustomed)  the  Ego,  Fichte 
understands  what  Kant  had  confusedly  in  his  mind  wlien 
he  spoke  of  the  jjure  as  opposed  to  the  emjnrical  Ego, 
the  pure  self-consciousness  which  is  the  basis  of  all 
empirical  thought,  and  which  the  Konigsberg  thinker 
subsequently  identifies  with  the  Practical  Reason.  Fichte 
clearly  enunciates  what  Kant  does  but  indistinctly  suggest, 
namely,  that  the  individual  Ego  is  in  the  order  of  tran- 
scendental deduction  at  the  opposite  pole  to  the  pure  Ego. 
What  was  with  Kant  merely  a  notion  arrived  at  more  or 
less  incidentally  in  the  course  of  the  working  out  of  his 
system,  becomes  with  Fichte  the  cornerstone  of  the  whole. 
The  attitude  of  the  philosopher  towards  pure  Egoition 
(Iclilieit)  is  not  that  of  mere  introspection,  but  it  may  be 
rather  termed  intellectual  intuition  in  which  individual 


ErocH  II.]  FICHTE.  201 

existence  parses  ont  of  view,  and  the  object  of  intuition  is 
not  so  nnich  existence  as  activity.  That  tliis  primary  act 
of  egoitioH  snthces  to  exjiLain  all  the  facts  of  conscionsness 
it  remains  for  the  development  of  the  system  to  show. 
Inasmuch  as  the  categories  are  only  so  many  momenta  or 
determinations  of  the  Ego,  and  inasmuch  as  it  is  they  which 
determine  the  possibility  of  the  object,  it  is  obvious  that  the 
latter  is  only  possible  in  so  far  as  it  is  given  by  the  Ego. 

The  second  axiom  of  Fichte  affirms  the  necessary  op- 
position of  the  non-ego  as  the  correlate  of  the  original 
position.  The  corresponding  logical  form  to  this  act  of 
op-position  (Anstoss)  is  A  is  not  B.  The  primary  act  of 
position  is  incomplete  without  this  secondary  act  of  op- 
position. With  the  fulfilment  of  these  two  postulates 
the  third  is  already  given,  for,  as  they  mutually  negative 
one  another  and  nevertheless  are  both  of  them  absolute — 
the  one,  absolute  affirmation,  the  other,  absolute  negation, 
their  synthesis  must  be  determination,  that  is,  the  abolition 
of  the  absolute  character  of  either  of  them  per  se,  and  the 
assertion,  so  to  speak,  of  absolute  relativity.  The  first 
axiom  was  unconditioned,  alike  as  regards  matter  and 
form ;  the  second  is  conditioned  as  regards  its  matter  but 
unconditioned  as  to  its  form;  the  third  is  unconditioned 
as  regards  its  matter  but  not  as  regards  its  form.  In 
these  three  axioms,  thesis,  antithesis,  and  synthesis,  we  have 
the  framework  of  the  Wissenschaftslehre. 

The  reader  will  observe  in  them  a  further  progress 
towards  the  completion  of  the  Dialectical  method.  Ac- 
cording to  Fichte,  we  have  here  the  categories  of  quality 
and  quantity  in  their  pure  form,  and  derive  them  from 
their  only  source.  In  this  primitive  synthesis  furnished 
by  (I.)  the  original  self-positing  I-ness  or  Egoition,  (II.) 
the  non-ego  posited  by  the  first  as  op-position  (Anstoss\ 
(III.)  the  resultant  limitation  of  the  former  by  the  latter, 
thereby  abolishing  its  absolute  character,  all  other  syn- 
theses are  contained,  ^\e  have  now  a  clear  road  before  us 
along  which  to  arrive  at  the  solution  of  Kant's  problem  : 
How  are  synthetic  propositions  a  priori  possible  ?  or,  which 
is  the  same  thing,  How  is  experience  possible  ?  a  road 
unencumbered  by  extraneous  and  useless  hypotheses  such 
as  "  things-in-themselves,"  &c. 


262  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Ei-och  II. 

As  yet,  however,  we  are  far  from  tlie  complex,  concrete 
synthesis — experience — of  which  we  are  in  search.  We 
must  first  see  whether  the  original  synthesis  itself  does 
not  contain  implicitly  its  own  antithesis,  which,  in  its 
turn,  may  pave  the  way  for  a  second  synthesis.  In  this 
analysis  or  search  for  antitheses,  and  their  combination 
into  syntheses  consists  the  method  of  philosophy,  a  method, 
as  before  observed,  already  shadowed  forth  by  Kant  in  his 
table  of  the  categories.  This,  of  course,  might  be  carried 
on  to  infinity,  were  it  not  that  the  thesis  embracing  all 
antitheses  and  syntheses,  the  self-identical  Ego  or  absolute 
principle  of  I-ness,  forms  at  once  the  starting-point  and 
limit  of  our  investigations.  The  goal  of  "  Theory  of 
Science"  namely,  is  to  reach  this  principle  which  is  its 
absolute  commencement  at  the  completion  of  the  circle  of 
its  journey.  It  then  appears  as  Kant's  "  law  giving  "  or 
*'  practical  "  reason,  as  a  striving  for  that  which  can  never 
be  fully  realised,  in  short,  it  re-appears  at  the  limit  of 
the  theoretic  and  practical,  as  idea.  Midway,  so  to 
speak,  between  the  absolute  commencement  and  the 
absolute  goal,  falls  the  finite,  limited,  divisible  Ego  of 
individuation.  The  third  axiom  or  S3'nthesis,  which 
embraces  the  whole  of  "  Theory  of  Knowledge,"  may  be 
briefly  formulated  thus  :  the  Ego  posits  itself  and  the  non- 
ego  as  reciprocal  and  determining.  It  is  plain  that  this 
proposition  involves  two.  First,  the  Ego  posits  itself  as 
determined  b}'  the  non-ego;  and  second,  the  Ego  posits 
itself  as  determining  the  non-ego.  In  this  distinction  is 
indicated  the  fundamental  division  of  "  Theory  of  Know- 
ledge "  itself  into  theoretical  or  speculative,  and  practical. 
The  first  has  to  solve  the  problem  of  Kant's  ^Esthetic  and 
Analytic,  namely,  how  the  Ego,  or  (which  is  the  same  thing 
with  Fichte)  the  pure  and  absolute  Eeason  can  arrive  at  a 
knowledge  of  the  object?  The  second  deals  with  the 
problems  of  Kant's  "Lialectic"  and  "Practical  Eeason," 
and  contains  the  answer  to  the  question :  How  does  the 
Ego  or  Eeason  come  to  ascribe  causality  to  itself? 


Epoch  II.]  FICIITE.  263 


Speculative  "Theory  of  Knowledge." 

"  Philosophy,"  says  Fichte  (  Werke,  vol.  i.  p.  425),  "  has  to 
assign  a  foundation  for  all  experience ;  its  object  therefore 
necessarily  lies  outside  all  experience  ....  finite  reason 
has  nothing  outside  experience ;  experience  contains  the 
whole  matter  of  its  thinking.  The  philosopher  necessarily 
stands  under  the  same  condition,  hence  it  seems  incom- 
prehensible how  he  can  lift  liimself  above  experience. 
But  he  can  abstract,  that  is,  he  can  separate  by  the 
free  action  of  his  thought  what  is  combined  in  experience. 
In  experience  the  thing,  namely,  that  which  is  determined 
independently  of  our  freedom,  and  to  which  our  knowledge 
has  to  direct  itself,  is  indissolubly  bound  up  with  the 
intelligence  which  cognises  it.  The  philosopher  can  make 
abstraction  from  either  of  them,  and  he  has  then  abstracted 
from  experience  and  raised  himself  above  it.  If  he 
abstracts  from  the  former,  he  retains  intelligence  per  se, 
that  is,  abstracted  from  its  relation  to  experience ;  if  he 
abstracts  from  the  latter,  he  retains  the  thing  per  se,  that  is, 
he  abstracts  from  the  fact  that  it  enters  into  experience; 
he  retains  it  as  the  only  ground  of  explanation  of  ex- 
perience. The  first  proceeding  is  called  Idealism,  the 
second  dogmatism^  So  much  as  to  the  standpoint  of  the 
older  philosophy  ;  but  what  as  to  that  of  "  Theory  of 
Science,"  which  cannot  rest  satisfied  any  more  with  the 
mind-in-itself  of  the  subjective  Idealists  than  the  thing- 
in -itself  of  the  dogmatists? 

Kant,  who  saw  that  the  empirical  idealist  and  the 
dogmatic  materialist  were  each  right  as  against  the  other, 
endeavoured  to  unite  them  mechanically.  Hence  his 
repudiation  alike  of  idealism  and  materialism  as  such,  and 
hence,  also,  his  characterisation  of  his  system  as  at  one  and 
the  same  time  empirical  realism  and  transcendental  idealism. 
This  mere  mechanical  combination  will  not  sufiBce  for 
Fichte.  "  Theory  of  knowledge "  requires  a  deduction 
from  one  central  principle.  The  "productive  imagination" 
of  Kant,  by  which  Fichte  understands  the  activity  of  the 
Ego  as  self-determining,  which  we  have  arrived  at  as  the 
original  synthesis  of  the  absolute  Ego  and  its  negation,  is 


26 1  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Eioch  II, 

the  basis  of  the  distinction  of  subject  and  object  on  which 
the  old  abstractions  turn.  We  now  see  wherein  tlie 
shortcoming  of  the  old  idealism  and  realism,  respectively, 
lay.  Inasmuch  as  the  presentation  is  for  the  Ego  a 
limitation  of  its  activit}^  it  is  regarded  as  foreign  to  it. 

Let  us  hear  Fichte  on  this  point.  "  Taking  our  stand 
firmly  at  the  point  at  which  we  are  arrived  (namely,  that 
of  the  primary  synthesis),  an  opposition  (Anstoss)  takes 
place  in  the  infinite  activity  of  the  Ego  wdiich,  because  it 
is  infinite,  contains  no  ground  of  distinction  ;  and  the 
activity  thereby  in  no  way  destroyed  is  reflected,  forced 
back,  and  thus  acquires  a  diametrically  opposite  direction. 
AVe  may  represent  the  infinite  activity  under  the  figure  of 
a  straight  line  passing  from  A  through  B  into  C,  &c.  It 
might  be  arrested  within  C  or  beyond  C.  Let  us  assume 
then  that  it  is  arrested  at  C.  The  ground  thereof  will 
then,  according  to  the  above,  lie  not  in  the  Ego  but  in  the 
Kon-Ego.  Under  the  given  condition  the  direction  of  the 
activity  of  the  Ego  going  from  A  to  C  is  reflected  from 
C  to  A,  but  nothing  can  act  upon  the  Ego,  in  so  far  as  it  is 
Ego  without  an  equivalent  reaction.  In  the  Ego  nothing 
can  be  destroyed,  not  even  the  direction  of  its  activity. 
Therefore  the  activity  reflected  towards  A  must,  in  so  far 
as  it  is  reflected,  at  the  same  time  react  to  C.  And  so 
between  A  and  C  we  have  a  double  conflicting  direction 
in  the  activity  of  the  Ego,  in  which  that  from  C  to  A  may 
be  regarded  as  passive,  and  that  from  A  to  C  as  mere 
activity  ;  both  together  constitutiug  one  and  the  same  state 
of  the  Ego.  This  state,  in  wdiich  diametrically  opposite 
diiections  are  united,  is  the  activity  of  the  '  imagination '  *  ; 
and  we  have  now  definitely  obtained  the  object  of  our 
search,  an  activity  which  is  only  possible  through  a 
passivity,  and  a  passivity  which  is  only  possible  through 
an  activity."    (Wevhe,  vol.  i.  p.  4G.) 

From  this  it  will  be  seen  why,  on  Fichtean  principles, 
an  Idealism  which  would  make  the  activity  of  the  Ego  the 
immediate  source  of  objects,  is  as  incorrect  and  onesided  as 
the  Realism  according  to  which  the  object- world  is  entirely 
independent  of  the  activity  of  the  Ego.       The  category  of 

*  Of  course  the  word  is  always  employed  in  a  trauscendcntal,  never 
in  an  empirical  sense. 


Erocii  II.]  FICHTE.  265 

Ideal-iealism,  as  Fichte  sometimes  calls  his  system,  is  not 
that  of  cau.se-and.-effect,  or  suhstaiice-and-accident,  but 
rather  that  of  action-and-reaction.  The  formula  for  the 
theoretical  or  speculative  :side  of  the  doctrine  is  indeed 
that  "  the  Ego  posits  itself  as  limited  or  determined  by 
the  Non-Ego;"  this  is  supplemented,  however,  on  the 
])ractical  side  by  the  formula,  "  the  Ego  posits  the  Non- 
Ego  as  determined  by  itself  (viz.  the  Ego)."  Objecrs 
then  are  given  us  through  the  ''  productive  imagination." 
Needless  to  say,  we  are  still  dealing  with  momenta  prior 
in  nature  to  empirical  consciousness.  The  object  appears 
here  merely  as  limitation.  It  yet  remains  for  Fichte  to 
deduce  the  remaining  stages  in  the  production  of  concrete 
experience.  In  this  exposition  (which  is  given  most 
fully  in  some  of  the  shorter  pieces  written  subsequently 
to  the  Grundlage  itself)  the  main  feature  is,  always  keeping 
in  view  the  fundamental  axiom  that  there  is  nothing  in 
the  Ego  but  what  is  posited  by  itself,  ihat  the  object  as 
object  is  a  reduplication,  so  to  speak,  of  the  original  act 
of  opposition,  in  other  wonls,  that  it  must  become  for 
itself  what  in  the  first  place  it  was /or  ws.*  The  Ego,  in 
order  to  reflect  on  any  moment  of  it  determination,  and 
thereby  to  constitute  it  object,  must  be  already  beyond 
that  moment — must  have  left  it  behind. 

The  first  stage  or  moment  is  that  of  in-itselfness,  mere 
feeling,  in  which,  as  yet,  there  is  no  distinction  between 
outer  and  inner,  feeling  and  felt.  In  the  next  stage  the 
Ego  distinguishes  itself  from  its  feeling,  and  views  the 
latter  as  in  a  sense  outside  itself.  In  this  moment  of 
outlooJcing,  feeling  becomes  difterentiated,  pluralised — it 
becomes  mutual  independence  (space)  and  onesided  in- 
dependence (time).  At  this  point,  says  Fichte,  the 
student  may  take  up  Kant's  Transcendental  Esthetic. 
Just  as  the  indefinite  possibility  of  feeling  becomes  by 
limitation  or  differentiation,  Intuition  (^Anschauung),  so  the 
indefinite  possibility  of  Intuition  becomes  fixed,  reduced  to 
actuality  by  the  limitation  imposed  upon  it  by  the 
Understanding  ( Verstand). 

In    the   syntheses    of    the   understanding   the   real  is 

*  This  is  important  in  view  of  the  Hegelian  Dialectic. 


266  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  TI. 

properly  contained.  The  intuitions  ordered  and  fixed  by 
its  categories  became  henceforward  real  objects.  The 
feeling  which  the  "  productive  imagination  "  distinguishes 
into  inner  and  outer  in  the  previous  moment  is  the  chaotic 
sense-world  of  Kant.  The  categories  must  not,  however, 
as  with  Kaiit,  be  regarded  as  so  many  ready-made  forms  or 
moulds,  but  rather  like  the  schemata,  as  modes  in  which 
the  "  productive  imagination  "  operates  in  its  creati(m  of 
objects.  The  necessity  for  smy  formal  deduction  of  the 
categories  is,  of  course,  done  away  with,  inasmuch  as  they 
fall  into  the  natural  cour.se  of  the  exposition  itself. 

The  intelligence,  when  it  passes  beyond  the  limits  fixed 
for  it  by  the  Understanding,  becomes  abstract  or  reflective  ; 
in  the  consciousness  of  the  possibility  of  this  consists  the 
*'  Pure  Reason "  of  Kant,  in  which  self-consciousness 
j)roper  is  first  explicitly  given.  The  intelligence  has  thus 
come  to  a  consciousness  of  itself  as  such  ;  the  circle  is 
complete.  "Theory  of  Science"  on  its  speculative  side 
is  now  perfect  as  a  system.  We  close  this  section  with 
a  quotation  from  Fichte  on  the  method  einploj'ed  in  the 
deduction  of  the  system  : — "  In  realising  this  deduction, 
he  (the  philosopher)  proceeds  as  follows :  He  shows  thai 
the  first  fundamental  law  which  ivas  discovered  in  immediate 
consciousness,  is  not  possihle,  unless  a  second  action  is  combined 
with  it,  luhich  again  is  not  possible  without  a  third  action ;  and 
so  on  until  the  conditions  of  the  first  are  cornjjletely  exhausted, 
and  it  is  itself  now  made  perfectly  comprehensible  as  to  its  possi- 
hility.  The  teacher's  method  is  a  continual  progression  from 
the  conditioned  to  the  condition.  The  condition  becomes 
again  conditioned,  and  its  condition  is  next  to  be  dis- 
covered. If  the  pre-supposition  of  Idealism  be  correct,  and 
if  no  errors  have  been  made  in  the  deduction,  the  last 
result,  as  containing  all  the  conditions  of  the  first  act, 
must  comprise  the  system  of  all  necessary  representations, 
or  the  totality  of  exjterience  ; — a  comparison,  however, 
which  is  not  instituted  in  philosophy  itself,  but  only  after 
that  science  has  finished  its  work."  (Fichte,  Werke, 
vol.  i.  p.  446.) 


Epoch  II.]  FICHTE.  267 


Practical  "Theory  of  Knowledge." 

Speculative  "  Theory  of  Science  "  while  explaining  the 
process  by  which  consciousness  comes  to  pass,  the  condi- 
tions of  its  possibility,  althongh  it  indicated  the  fact  of 
the  opposition  or  limiting  by  the  Ego  of  its  own  activity, 
failed  to  demonstrate  the  ground  of  this  limitation,  a  task 
reserved  for  the  practical  side  of  the  Fichtean  philosophy, 
which  lias  to  answer  the  question,  How  the  Ego  becomes 
conscious  of  itself  as  an  active  principle  in  the  events  of 
the  world  ? — in  short,  as  a  moral  agent.  The  answer  lies 
in  the  proposition  above  p;iven  as  constituting  the  formula 
of  the  practical  side  of  Fichte's  doctrine,  to  wit,  the  Ego 
posits  itself  as  determining  the  Non-Ego.  This,  which  is 
its  starting  point,  is  also  iis  goal.  Hence  the  supremacy 
Kant  had  already  averred  the  Practical  Eeason  to  possess 
over  the  Theoretical.  The  fundamental  axiom  of  "  Theory 
of  Knowledge  "  was  the  affirmation  by  the  Ego  of  its  own 
being  as  abs^olute.  The  question  now  arises.  How  is  the 
finite  objective  activity  which  has  been  deduced  reconcil- 
able with  this  basal  thesis?  only  in  one  way,  answers 
Fichte,  and  that  is,  If  the  finite  activity  be  conceived  as 
means,  and  the  infinite,  end.  This  occurs  when  the  Ego  is 
conceived  as  a  striving  towards  infiidty,  or,  practically 
expressed,  as  conscious  of  its  own  activity  as  cause,  which 
can  only  happen  in  so  far  as  it  overcomes  a  resistance ;  all 
striving  implying  resistance  to  be  overcome. 

*'  By  as  much  as  the  Ego  opposes  to  itself  a  Non-Ego,  it 
creates  limits  and  places  itself  in  these  limits.  It  distributes 
the  totality  of  the  existence  posited  generally,  between  the 
Ego  and  the  Non-Ego  ;  and  so  far  posits  itself  as  necessarily 
finite."  (^Werhe,  vol.  i.  p.  255.)  This  is  as  much  as  to 
say,  since  the  activity  of  the  Ego  is  now  no  longer  occupied 
with  itself,  but  with  the  Non-Ego,  it  has  become  objective 
(Fichte  clinches  his  argument  by  a  reference  to  the  German 
word  for  object  Gegenstand).  "  The  object  is  only  posited 
in  so  far  as  an  activity  of  the  Ego  is  resisted ;  no  such 
activity  of  the  Ego,  no  object.  The  relation  is,  that  of  the 
determining  to  the  determined.  Only  in  so  far  as  the 
above  activity  is  resisted  can  an  object  be  posited ;    and 


268  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

in  so  far  as  it  is  not  resisted  there  is  no  object."  (Ibid. 
259.)  The  object,  therefore,  is  necessary  to  the  realisation 
of  the  Ego's  activity  ;  it  creates  the  object-world  not  for  the 
sake  of  that  world,  but  for  the  sake  of  realising  itself  in  the 
negation  of  that  world.  The  Ego  thus  affirms  itself  in  a 
higher  form,  attains  reality,  in  other  words,  consciousness 
of  its  freedom,  in  the  negation  of  its  own  negation — in 
the  ovt!i  coming  of  that  resistance  which  it  has  set  up  over 
against  itt^elf. 

The  Ego  now  affirms  itself  as  Will.  The  correspon- 
dence of  Fichte's  doctrine  at  this  stage  with  that  of  Scho- 
penhauer, it  may  be  observed  in  passing,  is  noteworthy. 
Here  then  we  have  the  ground  of  the  original  antithesis  or 
opposition.  This  could  not  be  deduced  from  a  merely 
theoretical  or  speculative  point  of  view.  The  fii'st  division 
of  Theory  of  Science  was  obliged  simply  to  postulate 
the  antithesis  as  a  necessary  compliment  to  the  thesis, 
without  being  able  to  give  anj^  further  account  of  the 
matter.  "It  is  now,"  says  Fichte,  "obvious  how  this 
question  is  to  be  answered.  W  ith  the  positing  of  the  Ego 
all  reality  is  posited  ;  in  the  Ego  all  is  posited  ;  the  Ego 
must  be  absolutely  independent,  but  all  must  be  dependent 
upon  it.  The  agreement  of  the  object  with  the  Ego  is 
therefore  required,  and  the  absolute  Ego  it  is  which  for 
the  very  reason  that  its  being  is  absolute  requires  it." 
(Ibid.  260.)  Since  Theory  of  Knowledge  finds  its  highest 
ground  not  on  its  theoretical  but  on  its  practical  side,  it 
may  be  fitly  called  "  Practical  Idealism."  "  The  result  of 
our  investigations,"  says  Fichte,  "  is  accordingly  as 
follows :  The  pure  activity  of  the  Ego,  which  returns  in 
upon  itself,  in  respect  of  a  possible  object  is  a  striving,  and 
indeed,  as  above  shown,  an  infinite  striving.  This  infinite 
striving  is  to  all  infinity  the  condition  of  the  possibility  of 
all  object ;  no  striving,  no  object."  The  same  method 
obtains  in  the  practical  as  in  the  speculative  side  of  the 
doctrine — here  as  there  progression  is  spiral,  so  to  speak. 
The  in-itselfness  of  every  moment  of  determination  must 
become  a  for-itselfness  in  the  next  moment.  The  "  produc- 
tive imagination,"  the  striving  after  the  creation  and 
articulation  of  the  object,  becomes,  when  pursued  into  the 
region  of  the  practical,  the  striving  for  moral  satisfaction — 


Erocii  II.]  FICIITE.  209 

the  ethical  impulse  or  tendency.  The  basis  of  the  Ego  as 
"rrodnctive  imagination  "  was  the  Ego  as  Pure  Appercep- 
tion." The  goal  of  the  Ego  as  Freedom,  Tendency,  Will» 
is  the  Ego  as  Idea  or  Ideal.  The  Ego  as  Absolute  Subject 
is  unconditioned  Possibilifij ;  the  Ego  as  Ideal  is  un- 
conditioned Actiialiti/.  Noither  the  one  nor  the  other  can 
be  realised  in  the  plain  of  empii  ical  consciousness  which  is 
the  sphere  of  the  limited  or  conditioned,  although  its  know- 
ledge presupposes  the  first  and  its  ethical  impulses  the 
second.  In  this  the  essential  unity  of  the  S3'stem  is  shown. 
What  Avith  Kant  had  two  distinct  roots,  namely  the  theoreti- 
cal and  practical,  and  which  it  was  impossible  to  bring  into 
connection  otherwise  than  in  a  purely  mechanical  manner, 
is  by  Fichte  identified  in  one  fundamental  fact.  The 
categorical  imperative  "  the  ought  of  that  which  has  never 
happened  "  of  Kant,  becomes,  with  Fichte,  the  universal 
striving,  the  impulse,  manifested  on  the  one  side  in  the 
production  of  the  real  world  as  the  presentment  of  the 
Ego,  and  yet  as  independent  of  the  Ego,  and  on  the  other 
by  the  ethical  tendency,  the  aim  of  which  is  to  abolish 
this  independence  and  bring  it  back  into  subjection  to 
the  Ego. 

It  has  been  remarked  that  there  has  never  been  a 
system  so  antipathetic  to  "nature"  as  Fichte's.  Since  with 
Fichte  nature  is  identified  with  the  non-ego,  which  it  is  the 
ethical  function  of  the  Ego  to  abolish ;  his  position  with 
regard  to  it  is  identical  with  that  of  the  Buddhist  ascetic, 
for  whom  it  is  the  maija,  "  that  which  is  not  and  ought 
not  to  be,"  or  with  the  less  logical  Christian  ascetic.  This 
side  of  Fichte  we  shall  find  developed  in  Schopenhauer. 
Just  as  Kant  only  admits  theology  in  so  far  as  it  serves  as 
a  prop  to  Ethics,  so  does  Fichte.  He  stands,  moreover,  by 
the  distinction  of  Kant  between  the  legal  and  the  morale 
between  which  Fichte  maintains  that  there  is  no  sort  of 
connection,  the  object  of  law  being  to  supply  the  means 
by  which  its  mandates  are  to  be  maintained,  even  though 
justice  and  good  faith  should  have  vanished  from  among 
men.  Hence  law  justly  ignoies  morality,  for  morality 
deprives  law  of  its  raison  d'etre ;  the  just  man  being  a 
law  to  himself.  It  is  in  dealing  with  these  questions, 
more  especially  in  the   Grundlage  des  Natiirrechts  (^WerJce, 


270  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

vol.  iii.),  that  Fichte  gives  his  deduction  of  a  plurality  of 
individuals  or  rational  beings.  This  deduction  is  on  the 
same  lines  as  that  of  the  original  opposition  (Anstoss).  At 
first  sight  it  is  not  easy  to  comprehend  the  possibility  of 
deducing  from  the  one  indivisible  Subject,  or  impersonal 
Eeason,  the  plurality  of  individual  subjects,  but,  says 
Fichte,  the  Ego  must  be  conscious  of  itself  as  active,  that 
is,  must  "  ascribe  to  itself  a  free  activity  in  the  sense- 
world."  It  cannot  do  this  "  without  ascribing  it  to  others, 
and  therefore  assuming  other  finite  rational  beings  out!>ide 
itself." 

The  absolute  Ego  had  already  posited  objects  as  the 
material  for  its  activity  to  work  upon.  But  they  can 
only  serve  their  purpose  in  so  far  as  their  necessity  is 
given.  The  seal  is  affixed  on  this  necessity  when  the 
testimony  of  others  is  added  to  my  own.  The  universal 
Ego  or  I-ness,  which  is  the  condition  of  all  consciousness, 
mufet  therefore  posit  it>elf  as  individual  Ego  in  a  world  of 
individual  Egos,  united  under  the  categoiy  of  reciprocity. 
The  conception  of  individuality  "  is  obviously  a  reciprocal 
conception,  that  is,  one  which  can  only  be  thought,  in 
and  through  the  thought  of  another,  and  it  is  indeed  con- 
ditioned by  the  same  thought  as  to  its  form.  It  is  only 
possible  in  any  rational  being  in  proportion  as  it  is  given 
as  completed  by  another ;  it  is  therefore  never  mine,  but 
on  my  confession  mine  and  his,  Ms  and  mine ;  a  concep- 
tion common  to  both,  and  in  which  two  minds  are  united 
in  one.  .  .  .  The  complete  union  of  conceptions  de- 
scribed, is  only  possible  in  and  through  actions.  The 
consequence  therefore  is  that  it  consists  only  in  actions, 
and  can  only  be  required  for  actions.  Actions  occupy 
here  the  place  of  conceptions,  and  conceptions  in  them- 
selves apart  from  actions  do  not  and  cannot  concern  us." 
(Werhe,  vol.  iii.  pp.  47-48.) 

To  each  individual  Ego  a  portion  of  the  world- 
wh(»le  is  preseived  as  the  sphere  of  its  own  exclusive 
freedom,  and  the  limits  of  these  spheres  constitute  the 
rights  of  the  individual.  Within  its  own  sphere  the 
individual  Ego  justly  ascribes  to  itself  causality.  That 
portion  of  my  sphere  of  freedom  wliich  is  the  starting- 
point  of  all  the  changes  to  be  wrought  by  me  in  the  world 


Erocn  II.]  FKIHTE.  271 

of  sense,  is  my  body.  This  therefore  is  the  immediate 
object  of  right  or  law.  Tliere  can  be  no  question  of  any 
obligation  on  the  part  of  the  individual  to  enter  the  statu 
of  h\w,  but  once  entered  therein,  ir  foHows  as  a  natural 
consequence  that  be  respect  this  state.  We  see  evidences 
here  of  the  inevitable  social  contract  theor3\  Like  Kant, 
Ficbte  sees  in  the  state  the  instrument  fur  giving  sanction 
to  rights  by  force,  or,  as  he  miglit  define  it,  the  condition 
of  the  realisation  of  right.  Fichte's  view  of  the  state  is 
that  of  the  protector  of  the  personality,  in  other  words,  of  in- 
dividual freedom.  Property  he  considers  as  necessary  to  the 
maintenance  of  the  personality.  But  the  state  exists  for 
Fichte  merely  as  a  convenience,  wliose  highest  aim  should 
be  to  abolish  itself  by  rendering  itself  unnecessary.  We 
must  not  leave  this  subject  without  noticing  the  remark- 
able anticipations  of  Socialism  to  be  found  in  Fichte.  In 
his  early  essay  on  the  French  Eevolution  he  proclaims 
labour  the  sole  basis  of  wealth,  and  hence  the  sole  justi- 
fication f«»r  its  posse-sion.  In  speaking  of  the  collective 
organisation  and  subdivision  of  labour,  and  the  posses- 
sion by  each  citizen  of  the  full  product  of  his  labour 
and  this  alone,  he  says,  "  Property  will  thus  be  uni- 
versalised ;  none  would  have  superfluities  while  there 
were  any  wanting  necessaries,  for  the  right  of  property 
in  articles  of  luxury  has  no  foundation  while  any 
citizen  lacks  his  necessary  portion  of  property.  Agri- 
culturists and  workmen  will  associate  themselves  for  the  'pro- 
duction of  the  greatest  possible  amount  of  wealth  idth  the 
least  possible  amount  of  labour. "  Other  socinlistic  passages 
are  to  be  found  in  the  Geschlossene  Handelstaat.  "  Each 
desires  to  live  as  pleasantly  as  possible  ;  and  since  every 
man  demands  this,  and  no  one  is  either  mote  or  less  than 
man,  all  have  an  equal  right  to  make  the  demand.  The 
division  must  be  made  accordingly  on  the  basis  of  this 
equality,  so  that  each  and  all  may  live  as  pleasantly  as 
possible."  Fichte  boldly  proclaims  it  the  function  of  his 
"  state  "  to  secure  an  equal  enjoyment  of  the  products  of 
labour  among  its  members. 

Fichte's  Ethics  (Sittenlehre')  are,  like  the  "  Jurispru- 
dence "  (^Bechtslehre),  divided  into  three  sections,  the  tirst 
containing  the  deduction  of  the  principles  of  morality,  the 


272  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II 

second  dedncinG!;  its  reality  and  applicability,  and  the  third 
dealing  with  the  sj'stem  of  duties.  Fichte  maintains  in 
the  liist  the  necessity,  even  in  the  absence  of  any  end,  of 
regulating  action  in  accoidance  with  a  pre-determined 
standard,  to  be  the  fundamental  axiom  of  man's  moral 
nature.  He  here  expresses,  in  a  dry  hard  formula,  the 
basis  of  a  whole  school  of  Ethic — a  school  which  embraces 
all  the  so-called  Ethical  or  universal  religions  of  the 
world.  Wiapped  up  in  imagery,  in  rhetoric,  and  concealed 
b}"  theological  theories,  the  corner-stone  of  the  morality 
of  thcise  religions,  all  turn  upon  this  arbitrary  premiss,  if 
we  do  but  pursue  it  far  enough.  As  will  be  already 
apparent  to  the  reader,  it  is  a  legitimate  consequence  from 
what  Fichte  terms  the  practical  side  of  his  "  Theory  of 
Knowledge."  He  theie  showed  us  the  Ego  erecting  a 
world  over  against  itself  for  no  other  purpose  than  to 
realise  its  power  in  the  subjugation  of  that  world.  That 
the  individual  should  determine  his  actions  for  the  mere 
sake  of  determining  them,  is  the  necessary  coioUary  from 
this.  Fichte  has  the  merit  of  being  the  only  thinker 
who  has  grasped  the  ground  axiom  of  the  morality 
which  has  been  current  among  men  for  ages,  and  has 
logically  carried  it  out.  He  proceeds  to  develop  his 
doctrine  resjDCcting  the  moral  tendency  as  causal  factor  in 
the  events  of  the  world,  distinguishing  between  the 
sensuous  impulse,  or  impulse  to  happiness,  and  the  moral 
impuls^e.  The  moral  impulse  leads  to  a  satisfaction,  a 
happiness,  v/hich  could  never  be  obtained  were  it  the 
object  immediately  sought  after.  Ethical  theory  frees 
men  from  the  worship  of  this  idol,  happiness,  and  proclaims 
the  end  of  all  action  to  be  the  reallocation  of  the  Ego  as 
Idea,  viz.  the  "  moral  order  of  the  world,"  to  which 
Fichte  applies  the  teim  "  God."  This  is  the  basis  of  reli- 
gion as  understood  by  Fichte,  which  is  identified  with  the 
moral  impulse  in  its  highest  form.  Its  object,  as  idea,  can 
of  course  never  be  realised  in  empirical  consciousness ; 
the  relation  of  human  life  to  this  Idea  nmst  ever  remain 
like  that  of  the  asymptote  to  the  hyperbole,  a  continuous 
approximation,  a  becominuj  which  never  becomes,  which  is 
never  finished.  Jfichte  polemicises  ngainst  the  conception 
of  God  as  existing  object.     Those  who  conceive  the  Also- 


Epoch  II.]  FICHTE.  273 

lute  as  being  have  really  emptied  the  coiKjeptidn  of  its 
content.  It  is  oBvious  from  the  main  principle  of  Ficlite's 
philosophy  that  the  Absolute  must  not  be  considered  as 
an  existence  over  against  ourselves.  We  must  rather,  in 
our  own  peisonality,  be  it  and  live  it.  The  conception  of 
the  Deity  as  substance  or  personality,  in  however  vague  or 
refined  a  form,  Fichte  stigmatizes  as  the  last  remnant  of 
Taganism  from  which  it  is  the  function  of  "  Theory  of 
Knowledge  "  to  deliver  men ;  any  question  as  to  an  author 
of  the  "  moial  order  of  the  world,"  is  to  Fichte  just  as 
inadmissible  as  the  question  as  to  the  cause  of  the  Deity 
would  be  to  the  ordinary  Theist.  Existence  is  a  sensuous 
conception  which  has  no  locus  standi  in  these  matters. 
\V  ith  the  Ego  as  Idea,  as  "  the  moral  order  of  the  world," 
the  system  of  Fichte  reaches  its  final  conclusion.  It  is 
not  uncommon  to  divide  the  Fichtean  doctrine  into  two 
periods ;  the  later  developments  of  the  syNtem,  however, 
show  no  essential  points  of  diiference.  The  terminology 
employed  is  sometimes  more  carefully  chosen  wdth  a  view 
of  accommodation  to  the  Theological  faculty  which  had 
procured  his  expulsion  from  the  university  of  Jena,  but 
that  is  practically  all. 

With  Fichte,  as  with  Kant,  Ethics  is  conceived  ab- 
stractly. In  this  respect  the  systems  of  both  thinkers  may 
be  alike  regarded  m  the  light  of  attempts  to  reconstitute 
the  Christian  and  introspective  Ethics,  threatened  by  the 
collapse  of  the  dogmatic  system  of  which  they  form  part, 
on  a  more  secure  basis.  In  many  post-Kantian  thinkers, 
but  notably  m  Fichte,  we  find  this  deification  of 
morality  as  such,  this  assumption  of  morality  as  an 
end  in  itself,  nay,  as  the  telos  of  all.  A  great  deal  of  the 
enthusiasm  called  forth  by  Kant  may  oe  referred  to 
the  belief  that  he  had  rehabilitated  the  old  theological 
morality  against  the  mere  negations  of  the  revolutionary 
writers  and  effectually  rendered  it  independent  of  any 
theological  basis.  This  hope,  as  might  oe  imagined, 
proved  but  short-lived.  The  impossibility  of  a  Christian 
Ethic  apart  from  a  Christian  Theology  has  been  con- 
spicuously illustrated  in  the  collapse  of  the  Kantian 
and  pobt-Kantian  schools,  a  collapse  almost  wholly  trace- 
able to  their  staking  their  existence  upon  the  achievement 

T 


274  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  U. 

of  tins  impossible  feat.  The  fallacy  running  throughout 
them  may  be  found  in  the  hypostasis  of  the  mere  abstract 
form  of  the  moral  consciousness,  viz.  freedom.  The  effect 
of  this  galvanised  introspective  ethics  was  in  the  long  run 
decidedly  chilling.  Well  might  Maria  von  Herbert  com- 
plain to  Kant  that  when  put  seriously  to  the  test,  his 
*' categorical  imperative"  availed  her  nothing.  It  was  no 
abstract  "imperative"  or  "freedom,"  with  a  personified 
"  sum-total  of  all  reality,"  or  an  impersonified"  moral  order 
of  the  world "  as  its  goal  that  inspired  a  St.  Bernard,  a 
St.  Francis,  or  a  Thomas-a-Kempis.  The  ethics  of  inward- 
ness was  in  them  a  living  reality,  because  it  grew  out  of  a 
speculative  belief  which  to  them  was  a  living  reality  also. 

The  distinction  between  the  introspective  ethics  of 
the  old  Christian  theology  and  that  of  Kant  and  the 
post-Kantian s,  is  as  the  distinction  between  life  and 
electricity,  between  nature  and  art.  The  sooner  it  is 
recognised  that  the  "  ethics  of  inwardness "  is  a  part 
of  a  whole,  that  it  cannot  live  separately  from  a  particular 
conception  of  the  world,  and  of  man's  relation  to  the  world,  . 
in  other  words,  from  a  religion  of  the  supernatural  or  spiritual 
as  such,  the  better  for  consistent  thought.  The  non-recog- 
nition of  this  is  only  an  instance,  albeit  a  serious  one, 
of  the  common  fallacy  of  regarding  as  fundamental  in 
human  nature  what  is  merely  the  characteristic  of  a  special 
epoch  of  historic  evolution. 

In  the  earlier  periods  of  history, — not  to  speak  of 
the  vast  pre-historic  era — the  individual,  as  such,  did 
not  exist,  morally  speaking,  so  completely  was  he  ab- 
sorbed in  the  social  wh(jle — in  the  gens,  the  tribe,  the 
*'city."  Morality  was  then  purely  outward;  men  sac- 
rificed themselves  for  the  community  as  a  matter  of 
course ;  in  active  devotion  to  the  community  consisted 
all  religion  and  all  duty.  The  decay  of  the  old 
social  and  race  ideals  was  synchronous  with  the  rise 
of  another  religion  and  morality,  that  of  the  individual 
as  such.  This  was  the  religion  and  morality  taught  by 
the  so-called  "  ethical  religions  "  of  the  world,  and  which 
reached  its  ultimate  expression  in  Christianity.  It  formed 
part  of  a  new  conception  of  the  universe,  in  which  the 
old  standing-ground  was  radically  changed,  by  the  intro- 


Epoch  II.]  FICHTE.  275 

duction  of  the  notion  of  the  spiritual  over  against  the 
natural.  Religion  and  morality,  from  being  social  and 
natural,  became  individual  and  supernatural ;  the  test  of 
the  value  of  the  individual  was  no  longer  to  be  found  in 
his  relation  to  the  community  existing  without  him,  but 
in  his  relation  to  the  divinity  revealed  within  him.  The 
spiritual  or  the  supernatural  abhors  the  natural  as  mnch 
as  the  "  nature  "  of  our  grandfathers  abhorred  a  vacuum, 
and  hence  the  essence  of  the  ethics  of  "  inwardness  "  has 
alwavs  consisted  in  the  negation  of  the  "  natural  man," 
in  other  words,  in  self-renunciation  for  its  own  sake — in 
asceticism.  It  is  this  ethics  of  "  inwardness  "  which  Kant 
and  the  post-Kantian s  thought  to  rehabilitate  apart 
from  the  supernatural  theology,  with  which  it  is  both  logi- 
cally and  historically  connected.  The  most  pronounced 
representative  of  this  ill-fated  attempt  w^as  Fichte. 

The  author  of  the  WissenscJiaftslelire  proclaimed  in  all  its 
baldness  the  doctrine  that  the  negation  of  the  phenomenal 
individual  is  the  final  end  of  all  morality.  His  desire  to 
assert  the  ethics  of  inwardness  blinded  Fichte  to  the 
crudely  abstract  nature  of  the  doctrine  he  proponiided. 
As  the  outcome  of  supernatural  religion,  with  its  mystical 
relation  of  ttie  individual  to  the  divinity,  it  is  real  enonuh. 
The  necessity  of  connecting  it  with  something  corresponding 
to  the  old  "  spiritual ''  ground  was  vaguely  felt  by  Fichte, 
as  it  had  been  felt  by  Kant,  and  is  expressed  in  his  con- 
ception of  the  "  moral  order  of  the  world  "  as  idea ;  but 
the  support  was  too  weak  to  hold  it. 

All  morality  of  course  involves  a  j^f^ssible  sacrifice  of 
the  individual  in  the  interest  of  something  "  not  himself" 
as  individual.  The  fallacy  of  the  introspective  ethics 
when  proposed  as  a  rational  basis  for  conduct  consists  in 
treating  this  purely  abstract  element — this  negative 
moment — of  the  moral  consciousness  as  though  it  com- 
prised the  whole  concrete  synthesis  of  that  consciousness. 
Ethics,  concretely  viewed,  does  not,  as  the  doctrine  of 
inwardness "  assumes,  either  begin  or  end  with  the 
lindividual  per  se,  be  it  as  regards  affirmation  or  negation. 
Its  reference  to  the  individual  as  such  is  purely  secondary 
and  incidental. 

The  Fichtean  negation  of  the  natural  impulses  of  the 

T  2 


276  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  n. 

individual  is  therefore  utterly  barren  and  objectless,  since 
such  negation  only  acquires  meaning  when  directed 
to  a  definite  social  end.*  The  bare  form  of  the  mural 
consciousness,  freedom,  the  glories  of  which  Kant  and  his 
successors  trumpet  so  loudly,  is  a  mere  abracadabra  apart 
from  a  positive  content?  and  such  a  positive  content,  if 
not  furnished  it  by  the  arbitrary  mandates  of  a  supernatural 
being,  revealing  himself  directly  to  the  individual,  must 
be  sujiplied  by  the  needs  of  the  social  whole  into  which 
the  individual  enters.  The  determination  given  to  this 
'•  freedom,"  or  which  is  the  same  thing  otherwise  expressed, 
to  this  possibility  of  subordinating  directly  personal  in- 
terests to  those  which  may  be  termed  impersonal  (i.e.  as 
to  w^hat  natural  impulses  shall  be  suppret^sed,  and  what 
not  suppressed)  is  conditioned  entirely  by  the  forms  of 
the  social  environment. 

Any  ethic  which  leaves  this  out  of  account,  whether  it 
be  based  on  the  "  categorical  imperative,"  the  idea  of  the 
*'  moral  woi  Id-order,"  or  what  not,  remains  abstract  and 
dogmatic,  which  is  as  much  as  to  say,  it  belongs  to  the 
past  and  not  to  the  future.  As  a  matter  of  fact  neither 
Kant,  Fichte,  nor  their  successors  really  rested  satisfied 
wdth  the  abstractions  they  professed  to  glorify  ;  they  read 
into  their  categories,  and  necessarily  so,  the  current 
morality.  The  result  was  to  close  up  their  avenue  of 
vision  to  a  true  view  of  the  subject,  by  making  them 
postulate  the  morality  of  the  age  as  absolute. 

It  will  ])robably  have  been  evident  to  the  reader,  apart 
from  all  this,  that  there  is  a  distinct  line  of  cleavage 

*  In  Ethics,  if  anywhere,  we  have  presented  the  category  of  "  reci- 
procity," or  mutual  determination,  rather  than  that  of  "  causaUty,"  or 
one-sided  determination.  In  the  individual  resides  the  "  moral 
tendency,"  the  potentiality  to  the  pursuance  of  impersonal  aims.  This 
is  only  actualised,  only  receives  a  determination  when  the  individual 
is  regarded  as  entering  into  the  constitution  of  Society.  Here  the 
negation  of  individual  interest  is  realised  as  affirmation  of  social 
inteiest.  For  Fichte  and  his  school  {vide  supra)  society  exists  only  as 
food  (so  to  speak)  for  individual  '■  freedom '"  (i.e.  for  the  moral  impulses 
of  the  individual),  which  is  its  only  7-aison  d'etre.  This  monstrous  hypos- 
tasis is,  we  are  well  aware,  the  basis  of  tlie  current  morality,  but  it  is 
as  fallacious  a  "  subreption  "  as  any  which  Kant  gibbets  in  his  "  para- 
logisms." An  act  of  self-resti aint  apart  from  a  definite  social  end  is  as 
barren  ethically  as  a  proposition  respecting  "  pure  being'  ia  speculatively 


Erocn  II.]  FICIITE.  277 

between  the  speculafive  and  practical  sides  of  "  theory  of 
knowledge"  as  conceived  by  Fichte,  which  he  vainly 
endeavours  to  conceal.  The  fundamental  opposition 
between  the  moral  and  the  natural,  by  which  it  is  the 
function  of  the  Ego,  as  practical  activity,  to  abolish  that 
which  the  Ego,  as  theoretical  activity,  had  called  into  being, 
can  hardly  fail,  we  think,  to  strike  the  average  student  as 
a  result  somewhat  arbitrarily  imposed  upon  a  doctrine 
which  begins  by  annulling  the  absohiteness  of  the  dis- 
tinction between  the  Ego  and  the  non-Ego,  upon  which 
the  old  dualism  rested,  and  affirming  their  ultimate  unity. 
One  would  have  imagined  such  a  doctrine  should  rather 
have  led,  as  its  practical  issue,  to  a  "  rehabilitation  of  the 
body "  to  a  declaration  of  the  unity  of  man  and  nature, 
which  it  has  shown  to  be,  after  all,  a  part  of  the  ultimate 
essence — a  crucial  moment  in  the  realisation  of  con- 
sciousness— rather  than  to  an  Ethic  of  asceticism  and 
self-negation.  The  negation  of  natuie  would  then  mean 
merely  the  negation  of  its  antagonism  to  man,  not  the 
absolute  negation  for  which  Fichte  contended.* 

The  Wissenschaftslehre,  as  might  be  expected,  found 
oppositicm  not  only  from  the  representatives  of  pre-Kantian 
views,  whose  influence  and  numbers  by  this  time  had 
considerably  diminished,  but  also  from  the  Kantians  and 
semi-Kantians,  who  were  by  no  means  disposed  to  recognise 
Fichte  for  what  he  himself  claimed  to  be,  the  representa- 
tive of  the  logical  development  and  perfecting  of  the 
critical  system.  Not  to  mention  the  disciples  of  Kant,  who 
all  took  up  the  quarrel,  the  master  himself  disclaimed 
all  connection  or  sympathy  with  Fichte  in  the  most 
emphatic  manner.  Jacobi  and  his  school  also  joined  in  the 
onslaught.  The  Wissenschaftslehre  thus  found  itself  simul- 
taneously attacked  by  Kantians,  pre-Kantians,  and  religious 
illuminists.  In  addition  to  these,  there  were  of  course  the 
popular  writers,  who,  in  spite  of  protestations  and  expla- 

*  For  an  interesting  account  of  the  life  and  philosophy  of  Fichte,  the 
student  is  referred  to  Professor  Adamson's  '  Fichte,'  in  Blackwood' :< 
series.  This  Uttle  volume  also  contains  one  of  the  clearest  condensed 
statements  in  popular  English  of  the  *'  speculative "  principle  and 
method,  that  we  have  seen. 


278  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

nations,  persisted  in  treating  the  absolute  Ego  of  Fichte  as 
though  it  referred  to  the  individual  Ego,  and  who  amused 
themselves  and  their  readers  by  affirming  that  "  Professor 
Fichte  regarded  himself  as  the  Creator  of  the  world."  But 
notwithstanding  the  opposition  raised  against  him,  Fichte 
succeeded  in  gathering  together  a  small  but  enthusiastic 
circle  of  disciples.  Foremost  among  these  was  the  thinker 
with  whom  we  shall  next  have  to  deal. 


SCHELLING. 

Frederick  Wilhelm  Joseph  Schelling  was  born  January 
27,  1775,  at  Leonburg  in  Wiirtemburg.  In  his  sixteenth 
year  he  entered  the  Theological  Seminary  at  Tubingen, 
where,  in  addition  to  theology,  he  occupied  himself  with 
philosophical  and  philological  studies.  Some  years  later 
lie  went  to  Leipzig,  where  he  devoted  himself  chiefly  to 
Mathematics  and  Natural  Science. 

In  1798,  he  taught,  together  with  Fichte,  at  Jena;  in 
1803  he  was  called  to  the  chair  of  philosophy  at  Wiirzburg. 
He  became  subsequently  secretary  to  the  Academy  of 
Sciences  at  Munich,  after  which  he  lectured  at  Erlangen 
for  some  years.  The  last  official  position  he  held  was  in 
the  university'  of  Berlin,  but  this  he  gave  up  some  years 
before  his  death,  which  took  place  in  Switzerland,  August 
20, 1854.  Schelling's  works,  which  occupy  14  volumes,  were 
published  in  a  complete  edition,  between  1856  and  1860. 

System  of  Identity. 

Schelling's  Philosophy,  or  "  The  System  of  Identity,"  as 
he  termed  it,  exhil)its  some  not  inconsiderable  variations 
in  its  earlier  and  later  form.  As  already  intimated,  Schelling 
was  originally  a  follower  of  Fichte.  His  fundamental 
divergence  from  the  WissenscJiaftslehre  consit^ted  in  an 
accentuation  of  the  indifference  of  the  basal  principle  of 
knowledge  as  regards  the  distinctions  of  subjective  and 
objective,  real  and  ideal,  mind  and  nature.  These  and  all 
minor  distinctions  are  implicitly  contained,  and  yet 
resolved,  in  the  original  identity,  the  Absolute. 

The  Idealism  of  Fichte,  Schelling  found  to  be  too  sub- 


Epoch  II.]  SCHELLING.  279 

jective.  AYe  have  already  seen  that  Fichte  started  with 
the  Ego  as  the  primordial  activity',  which  all  knowledge 
presupposed,  to  end  with  the  Ego  as  Idea,  which  all 
morality  presupposed.  The  Fichtean  system  is  thus  to 
some  extent  open  to  the  criticism  Fichte  had  himself 
made  as  regards  the  "  Critical  Philosophy,"  namely,  tliat 
it  did  not  form,  so  to  speak,  a  complete  circle.  The  fault 
is,  according  to  Schelling,  that  it  was  one-sided;  that 
although  it  might  lay  claim  to  the  title  of  "  Ideal- Realism," 
it  could  not  be  called  at  the  same  time  "  Real-Idealism." 

Knowledge  consisting  of  an  agreement  of  an  objective 
with  a  subjective,  the  problem  of  Philosophy  or  "  Theory 
of  Knowledge,"  is,  according  to  Schelling,  to  determine 
how  the  object,  the  sum-total  of  which  we  call  nature,  can 
enter  into  consciousness,  and  also  how  the  subjective,  or 
rather  the  sum -total  of  its  determinations,  mind,  or 
intelligence,  can  become  object  as  part  of  nature.  "  The 
sum  of  all  that  is  purely  objective  in  our  knowledge  we  may 
call  Nature,  while  the  sum  of  all  that  is  subjective  may  be 
designated  the  Ego,  or  Intelligence.  These  two  concepts 
are  mutually  opposed.  Intelligence  is  originally  conceived 
as  that  which  solely  represents  Nature,  as  that  which  is 
merely  capable  of  representation ;  the  former  as  the 
conscious  ;  the  latter  as  the  unconscious.  There  is,  more- 
over, necessary  to  all  knowledge,  a  mutual  agreement  of 
the  two — the  conscious,  and  the  unconscious  per  se.  The 
problem  is  to  explain  this  agreement."  Philosophy 
thus  necessarily  falls  into  two  main  divisions,  "  Nature- 
Philosophy,"  which  deals  with  the  problem,  so  to  speak, 
of  the  subjectivisation  of  the  object  and  "  Transcen- 
dental Philosophy,"  which  treats  of  the  objectivisation 
of  the  subject.  "  Transcendental  Philosophy,"  in  Schel- 
ling's  seuse,  regards  Nature  as  the  visible  organism 
of  the  Understanding,  while  "  Nature-Philosophy "  has 
to  explain  the  Understanding,  as  a  product  of  Nature. 
In  order  to  account  for  the  progress  of  Nature  from 
the  inorganic  to  the  organic  and  psychic,  Schelling 
has  recourse  to  the  time-honoured  theory  of  a  woiid- 
fashioning  principle  or  world-soul.  "  The  necessary 
tendency  of  all  natural  science,"  says  Schelling,  "  is  to 
proceed  from  Nature  to  Intelligence,  this  and  nothing  else 


280  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [ErocH  II. 

lies  at  the  basis  of  the  endeavour  to  reduce  natural 
phenomena  to  tiieory.  The  completed  theory  of  nature 
would  be  one  which  resolved  the  whole  of  nature  into 
intelligence.  The  dead  and  unconscious  products  of  nature 
are  only  the  unsuccessful  attempts  of  nature  to  become 
conscious  of  itself.  Dead  nature  is  only  unripe  intelli- 
gence, hence  its  phenomena,  notwithstanding  that  they 
are  unconscious,  reveal  a  character  of  intelligence.  The 
final  goal  of  becoming  completely  object  to  irself  is  attained 
by  nature  in  its  highest  and  final  reflection,  which  is 
nothing  other  than  man,  or,  expressed  more  generally,  than 
what  we  term  Eeason.  It  is  here  that  natuie  first  returns 
completely  in  upon  itself,  whereby  it  is  evident  that  nature 
is  originally  identical  with  that  which  is  in  us  recognised 
as  conscious  and  intelligent." 

Transcendental  Philosophy  has  for  its  prol>lem  to  deduce 
the  necessity  of  our  assumption  that  things  exist  outside 
of  us.  It  is  not  within  everyone's  power  to  do  this,  but 
it  requires  a  special  faculty,  that  of  "  internal  intuition." 
The  philosopher  seizes  the  act  of  self-consciousness  in  the 
moment  of  its  becoming.  In  this  of  course  Schelling  is  in 
agreement  with  Fichte.  Inasmuch  as  iu  the  free  act  of 
the  Ego,  no  other  being  is  posited  but  itself,  it  has  to 
make  an  arbitrary  act  its  object.  The  task  of  Transcen- 
dental Philosophy  on  its  theoretical  side  is  from  this  act 
to  deduce  the  necessity  present  in  objective  experience. 
"  The  one  fundamental  prejudice  to  which  all  others  ar& 
reducible,  is  this  :  that  there  are  things  outside  of  us  ;  an 
opinion  which,  while  it  rests  neither  on  proofs  nor  on 
conclusions  (lor  there  is  not  a  single  irrefragable  proof  of 
it),  and  yet  cannot  be  uprooted  by  any  opposite  proof 
(naturam  furcd  ex^eUas,  taraen  usque  7'edihit),  lays  claim  to 
immediate  certainty ;  whereas,  inasmuch  as  it  refers  to 
something  quite  different  from  us — yea,  opposed  to  us— 
and  of  which  there  is  no  evidence  how  it  can  come  into 
immediate  consciousness,  it  must  be  regarded  as  nothing 
more  than  a  prejudice — a  natural  and  oiiginal  one,  to  be 
sure,  but  nevertheless  a  prejudice.  The  contradiction 
lying  in  the  fact  that  a  conclusion  which  in  its  nature 
cannot  be  immediately  certain,  is,  nevertheless,  blindly  and 
without  grounds,  accepted  as  Buch,  cannot  be  solved  by 


Evor:u  II.]  SCHELLING.  281 

transcendental  philosophy,  except  on  the  assnmption  that 
this  couclnsion  is  implicit]}',  and  in  a  manner  hiiheito  not 
manifest,  not  founded  upon,  but  identical,  and  one  and  the 
same  with  an  affirmation  which  is  immediately  certain  ; 
and  to  demonstrate  this  identity  will  really  be  the  task  of 
transcen  dental  philosophy." 

Schelling  divides  the  process  of  the  production  of 
the  Keal  into  three  stages;  the  first  extending  from 
original  blind  feeling  to  productive  intuition.  Feeling,  as 
given  limitation,  has  its  ground  in  a  previous  activity 
which  cannot  fall  within  consciousness,  inasmuch  as  its 
result,  passive  limitation  of  feeling,  is  the  primordial  stage 
of  consciousness.  The  progress  from  this  stage  to  the 
following  one  consists,  according  to  Schelling,  in  the  out- 
going of  the  infinite  activity  beyond  its  previous  point  of 
determination ;  what  it  then  was /or  us  it  now  is  for  itself. 
At  this  point  Schelling  seeks  to  show  why  the  perceived 
or  intuited  feeling  must  appear  spacially  in  three  dimen- 
f^ions,  in  other  words,  as  matter.  Then  begins  the  second 
period,  from  p-oductive  intuition  to  reflection.  Here  again, 
the  course  of  the  deduction  consists  in  showing  how  the 
intuition  comes  to  be  for  itself  what  it  was  previously 
for  the  act  of  contemplation.  This  period  contains  the 
whole  multiplicity  of  the  objective  world  as  the  con- 
sciousless  pioduction  of  the  Ego,  besides  the  deduction  of 
time  and  space  and  the  categories,  which  latter,  however, 
are  much  reduced  by  Schelling,  the  categories  of  relation 
being  indicated  as  the  ground  of  all  the  rest. 

1  he  category  of  Eeciprocity  phenomenalised  in  time  and 
space  is  expressed  in  Organisation.  The  interconnection  of 
the  parts  of  an  organism  is  not  a  case  of  cause  and  effect,  but 
of  action  and  reaction.  The  universe  viewed  under  the 
category  of  reciprocity  may  thus  be  regarded  as  an  organic 
whole.  In  this  also  is  given  the  ground  of  individuation 
in  the  subject,  the  explanation  why  the  Ego  hitherto 
limited  merely  by  the  object  in  general,  passes  into  a 
second  limitation  by  which  it  is  compelled  to  intuite  the 
universe  from  certain  limited  points  of  view,  each  one  of 
which  stands  in  the  relation  of  accident  to  the  sum  of 
things.  The  third  epoch  embraces  a  third  limitation, 
which  is  the   foundation  of  Will.     It  is  clear   that   the 


282  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II 

question  wliy  I  regard  a  portion  of  tlie  -universe  as 
specially  belonging  to  myself,  as  my  organism,  is  intimately 
connected  with  the  question,  how  I  come  to  regard  the 
remainder  of  the  universe  as  altogether  independent  of 
myself?  Schelling's  answer  to  this  is  that  it  takes  place 
through  an  act  of  will.  The  transition  from  the  theoretical 
to  the  practical  sides  of  Schelling's  philosophy  are  thus 
effected  in  a  manner  precisely  analogous  to  that  of  Fichte. 
There  is  little  indeed  in  Schelling's  transcendental  deduc- 
tion which  shows  any  essential  variation  on  the  correspon- 
ding division  of  the  Wissenschaftslehre.  The  gist  of  the 
deduction  is  well  given  by  Schelling  himself  when  he  says, 
"  As  natural  science  produces  idealism  out  of  realism,  by 
mentalising  the  laws  of  Nature  into  the  laws  of  intelli- 
gence, t)r  superinducing  the  formal  upon  the  material,  so 
transcendental  philosophy  produces  realism  out  of  idealism, 
by  materialising  the  laws  of  nature,  or  introducing  the 
material  into  the  formal." 

In  his  practical  philosophy  Schelling  is  still  mainly  at 
one  with  Fichte.  What  Fichte  calls  the  deduction  of  the 
opposition  (Anstoss)  constitutes  the  starting-point.  The 
act  of  wdll  has  to  be  explained,  the  inherent  contradiction 
between  freedom  and  necessity  which  must  be  conceived 
as  united  in  it  has  to  be  resolved.  The  category  of 
reciprocity  effects  this,  inasmuch  as  it  is  shown  that  this  is 
brought  about  by  the  action  of  intelligences  outside  the 
individual  Ego.  The  co-operation  of  many  intelligences 
produces  a  world  common  to  all.  Through  the  inter- 
action of  individual  intelligences  arises  the  limitation 
of  individuality.  The  world  common  to  all  is  the 
arena  of  our  conscious  action,  the  sphere  within  which 
we  know  ourselves  as  causal  agents.  This  turns  ujDon  the 
fact  (and  here  Schelling's  substantial  agreement  with 
Schopenhauer  comes  into  view)  that  what  we  call  action 
is  only  a  modified  form  of  perception,  since  perception 
itself  is  ultimately  nothing  but  unconscious  action.  For 
this  reason,  i.e.  because  they  are  ultimately  identical, 
Nature  and  Freedom  can  never  really  conflict.  How  at 
once  the  objective  world  conforms  itself  to  ideas  in  us,  and 
ideas  in  us  conform  themselves  to  the  objective  world,  it 
is  impossible  to  conceive,  unless  there  exists  between  the 


Epoch  II.]  SCHELLIXG.  283 

two  worlds  (the  ideal  and  the  real)  a  pre-established 
harmony.  But  this  pre-established  harmony  itself  is  not 
conceivable,  unless  the  activity,  whereby  the  objective 
world  is  produced,  be  originally  identical  with  that  which 
displays  itself  in  volition,  and  vice  versa. 

"Now  it  is  undoubtedly  a  (productive)  activity  that 
displays  itself  in  volition;  all  free  action  is  productive 
and  productive  only  with  consciousness.  If,  then,  we 
suppose,  since  the  two  activities  are  one  only  in  their 
principle,  that  the  same  activity  which  is  productive  loith 
consciousness  in  free  action,  is  productive  without  conscious- 
ness in  the  production  of  the  world,  this  pre-established 
harmony  is  a  reality,  and  the  contradiction  is  solved.'' 
Freedom  can  never  transcend  the  laws  of  Nature,  and  the 
fact  that  impulse  falls  within  the  sphere  of  Nature,  does 
not  aifect  its  intrinsic  character.  (This,  be  it  observed,  is 
nothing  but  Kant's  phenomenal  necessity  united  with 
noumenal  freedom  otherwise  put.)  Schelling  proceeds  to 
build  up  on  the  basis  of  the  above  a  social,  political,  and 
historical  theory,  which,  in  spite  of  occasional  suggestive- 
ness,  shows  no  real  advance  upon  Fichte. 

The  main  difference  between  Schelling  and  the  author 
of  the  Wissenschaftslehre  appears  conspicuously  in  the 
"  Philosophy  of  Art,"  and  here  again  we  find  a  striking 
correspondence  with  Schopenhauer.  The  fundamental 
distinction  between  nature  and  art  is  that  between  con- 
scious and  unconscious  production.  Nature  has  the 
appearance  of  design  without  being  consciously  formed 
according  to  design.  The  Ego  is /or  itself  smd  in  itself,  at 
one  and  the  same  time  conscious  and  unconscious,  in  the 
art-perception.  In  art,  which  is  the  product,  so  to  speak, 
of  an  inspiration  which  is  itself  unconscious,  consciously 
exercised,  is  realised  that  Ideal  which  practice  or  morality 
is  ever  striving  to  attain  but  never  reaches.  Art  is  the 
resolution  of  an  infinite  contradiction ;  beauty  is  the 
incomprehensible  miracle  by  which  the  ideal  is  materialised 
and  the  material  is  idealised,  by  which  Nature  is  pre- 
sented as  the  infinite  possibility  of  freedom,  and  freedom 
as  the  definite  reality  of  Nature. 

The  aesthetic  faculty  occupies  the  same  pre-eminent 
position    with    Schelling    that    the    moral    impulse    or 


284  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

conscience  does  with  Fichte.  Artistic  perception  is  the 
objectivised  transcendental.  Art  and  philosophy  have  it 
in  common  that  their  subject-matter  is  a  reality,  but  an 
idealised  reality.  The  production  of  the  artist  and  of  the 
philosopher  is  alike  a  reproduction  of  the  world  which  is 
in  himself.  The  eesthetic  or  artistic  consciousness  forms 
therefore  the  conclusion  of  the  system.  Its  commence- 
ment is  intellectual  intuititm,  its  close  is  artistic  intuition. 
Intellectual  intuition,  inasmuch  as  it  does  not  fall  directly 
within  empirical  consciousness,  can  only  be  appreciated  by 
the  philosopher  who  can  distinguish  ir,  and  hence  philo- 
sophy, as  philosophy,  will  never  be  available  for  everybody. 
The  aesthetic  intuition,  on  the  contrary,  is  merely  the 
highest  and  most  complete  phase  of  empirical  consciousness, 
and  therefore  art  is  available  for  all,  potentially,  if  not 
actually.  As  Philosophy  and  Poetry  were  in  the  infancy 
of  mankind  united  in  Mythology,  so  its  maturity  wdll 
produce  a  new  mythologj',  which  wall  present  in  idealised 
form,  not  the  history  of  any  individual  hero,  but  of  the 
whole  human  race. 

The  departure  of  Schelling  from  Fichte  is  crucially 
shown  in  his  constituting  "  Philosophy  of  Nature,"  co- 
ordinate with  *'  Transcendental  Philosophy."  In  this,  ob- 
viously, "  Transcendental  Philosophy  "  is  conceived  as  a 
science  purel}'  of  the  subjective,  to  which  a  corresponding 
science  of  the  objective  is  a  necessary  complement.  The 
opposition  between  them  is  resolved  by  Sclielling's  notion 
of  the  Absolute  as  pure  "  inditit'erence  "  or  '•  identity."  In 
philosophy  of  Nature,  Nature  is  regarded  as  productive 
(iiatura  naturans),  not  as  product  (natura  naturata). 
Nature  is  here  viewed  as  self-limiting  productivity;  oa 
the  one  hand  maintaining  its  own  infiniry,  while  at  the 
same  time  crystallising  itself  in  limited  products  or 
phenomena.  As  the  stream  flows  endlessly  on,  notwith- 
standing the  continuous  passage  into  notliingness  of  its 
individual  drops,  so  it  is  wdth  Nature ;  it  is  ceaselessly 
creating  and  annihilating  itself  in  its  products.  Nature 
may  thus  be  viewed  as  a  struggle  between  the  principles 
of  universalisation  and  individuation,  a  struggle  mani- 
fested in  a  series  of  attempts,  so  to  speak,  to  realise  an 
equilibrium.     This  is  called  by  Schelling  the  *'  dynamic 


Epoch  IL]  SCIIELLING.  285 

process  "  of  Nature,  and  is  worked  out  by  him  in  the  form 
of  an  emanation- theory. 

Schelling,  as  we  have  already  seen,  defines  the  Absolute 
Reason  as  the  complete  indifference  between  object  and 
subject.  This  conception  is  attained  by  distinguishing^ 
between  the  act  of  thinking  and  the  thought.  This 
absolute  identity  is  the  true  in-it>self-ness  of  things,  and  to 
know  "things  in  themselves,"  is  to  know  them  as  they 
are  in  the  Absolute  Reason. 

The  "  absolute  identity "  of  Schelling  is,  in  spite  of 
Schelling's  protestations  to  the  contrary,  in  no  way 
distinguishable  from  the  absolute  Ego  of  Fichte,  all 
quantitative  diiference,  of  course,  falling  within  the 
region  of  the  finite.  The  fundamental  formula  for  the 
Absolute  being  A  =  A,  that  for  the  Relative  is  A  =  B, 
subject  and  object  being  combined  in  various  proportions. 
In  itself  of  course,  nothing  is  relative.  Were  we 
able  to  take  in  the  universe  in  an  "  infinite  glance," 
we  should  discover  perfect  quantitative  equilibrium 
between  isubjective  and  objective  ;  it  is  only  in  individual 
things  that  proportionate  differences  between  these  two 
elements  occur.  There  is  nothing  outNide  the  whole ; 
the  notion  of  anything  existing  apart  from  the  system 
of  things  which  is  the  manifestation  of  the  Absolute 
is  due  TO  the  error  of  reflection  which  separates  and 
individualises  the  inseparable  and  the  universal.  The 
quantitative  differences  existing  in  finite  things  as  to  the 
subjective  or  objective  element  they  contain  are  termed 
by  Schelling  iwtences.  The  first  potence  is  matter  in 
which  the  two  elements  or  momenta  are  united  as  gravity. 
Here  we  have  the  preponderance  of  the  object ;  the  second 
is  light,  the  preponderance  of  the  subject ;  the  third  is 
the  synthesis  of  both— organisation — wliich,  according  to 
Schelling,  is  common  to  all  matter.  The  con  espondence 
of  Schelling  with  Leibnitz  is  apparent  when  he  speaks  of 
inorganic  matter  as  a  sleeping  plant  and  animal  world. 
The  doctrine  of  evoluti(m,  it  cannot  be  denied,  is  distinctly 
present  in  Schelling's  Naturpkilosophie.  Man  is  simply 
the  result  of  the  entire  process  of  organic  metamorphosis. 
"What  we  term  inorganic  matter,  contains  within  itself  the 
potentiality  of  life ;  it  represents,  in  its  present  form,  the 


286  MODERN  PHILOSOrHY.  [Epoch  H. 

abortive  product  of  the  attempt  of  nature  to  become 
organic.  In  the  ideal  sphere  the  potences  are,  Knowledge, 
Action,  and  Reason.  The  first  gives  ns  the  "  true,"  the 
subsuming  of  matter  under  form  ;  the  second  the  "  good," 
the  subsuming  of  form  under  matter ;  and  the  third,  the 
synthesis  of  these — the  "  beautiful." 

The  later  developments  of  Schelling  show  an  ever 
increasing  tendency  to  go  off  into  mere  mysticism  and 
theosophy.  From  1804  onwards  a  strong  Xeo-platonic 
bias  is  shown  in  all  his  writings.  This  culminated  after  a 
lengthened  study  of  the  mediseval  mystics  of  Germany, 
and  of  Jacob  Boehme,  in  literary  productions  which 
amount  to  little  more  than  fantastic  rhapsodies  of  a 
religio-poetical  nature.  The  exposition  of  these  need  not 
detain  us,  inasmuch  as  they  have  no  important  bearing  on 
the  subsequent  history  of  philosophy  in  Germany,  such 
influence  as  they  exerted  being  purely  on  mystical 
litterateurs,  such  as  Schlegel,  Tieck,  Novalis,  &c.,  if  we 
except  some  slight  impulse  they  may  have  given  to 
mythological  studies. 

Schelling's  system  as  a  whole  can  hardly  be  regarded 
as  embodying  auy  solid  advance  on  Fichte,  although  there 
are  certain  departments  in  which  Fichte  was  especially 
lacking  upon  which  Schelling  is  suggestive.  This  is 
notably  the  case  as  regards  Art.  Fichte,  like  Kant,  in  his 
apotheosis  of  that  emptiest  of  all  simulacra  "  moral 
freedom,"  entirely  ignores  the  Art-consciousness.  In 
Schelling's  Philosophy  of  Art,  though  there  is  much  that 
is  artificial  and  of  no  speculative  value,  there  are  also 
some  luminous  thoughts  of  which  Hegel  and  later  writers 
on  Esthetics  have  availed  themselves.  As  regards 
method,  Schelling  is  distinctly  retrograde,  if  indeed  he 
can  be  said  to  have  any  method  at  all.  His  system  is, 
moreover,  based  upon  the  purely  psychological  distinction 
of  subject  and  object,  the  importance  of  which  Fichte  had 
to  some  extent  gauged  at  its  true  value.  Schelling 
assumes  the  distinction  as  ultimate,  and  then  endeavoui*s 
to  transcend  it  by  a  mere  phrase.  Well  might  Hegel 
complain  that  Schelling's  Absolute  appears  in  his  system 
"  as  though  it  had  been  shot  out  of  a  pistol."  The  l^ter 
writings  of  Schelling  show  him  to  have  been  essentially 


Epoch  II.]  SCHELLING.  287 

rather  what  the  Germans  called  a  sclwngeist — the  cultured 
man  of  letters  with  a  religio-a3sthetic  cast  of  mind — than 
the  philosopher  pure  and  simple. 

The  "  System  of  Identity  "  succeeded  in  obtaining  a 
following,  not  only  in  the  philosophical  world,  but, 
as  was  to  be  expected,  amongst  purely  literary  men. 
It  was  eminently  congenial  to  the  spirit  of  the  romantic 
school,  then  in  the  height  of  its  renown.  That  it  should 
have  attracted  men  of  science,  may  seem  somewhat 
surprising,  yet  so  it  was.  The  naturalist,  Oken,  the 
botanist.  Von  Esenbeck,  the  physiologist,  Buidach,  among 
others  may  be  mentioned  as  disciples  of  Schelling.  Among 
the  philosophical  adherents  and  expanders  of  the  system 
may  be  named,  G.  M.  Klein,  J.  J.  Wagner  the 
theosophist,  F.  Von  Baader  and  K.  C.  F.  Krause.  The 
two  latter,  although  they  are  sometimes  regarded  as 
the  founders  of  independent  systems,  have  in  all  essen- 
tials drawn  from  Schelling.  The  celebrated  theologian 
Schleiermacher  also  belonged  to  the  school  of  Schelling. 

Before  entering  upon  an  analysis  of  Hegel's  system, 
which  at  least,  so  far  as  method  is  concerned,  forms  the 
culmination  of  the  line  of  thought  we  have  been  consider- 
ing, we  propose  to  turn  aside  in  order  to  take  a  survey  of 
two  other  schools  of  thought,  which  also  have  their 
origin  in  the  "  Critical  Philosophy."  Kant,  as  we  know, 
makes  an  absolute  distinction  between  Sensibility  and 
Understanding.  Sense  is  always  with  Kant  the  material 
principle.  Understanding,  the  formative  principle,  in  the 
synthesis  of  Eeality.  "  Esthetic  "  and  "  Analytic  "  are 
the  two  co-ordinate  pillars  on  which  the  structure  of  the 
Critical  Philosophy  rests.  The  Sense-element  in  Know- 
ledge is  as  incapable  of  reduction  to  terms  of  the  Under- 
standing as  the  Intelligible-element  is  to  terms  of  Sense. 
Fichte,  in  his  deduction  of  experieoce  from  the  one  funda- 
mental principle  of  Egoition,  took  his  stand  on  Kant's 
formal  element,  the  Understanding,  the  starting-point  of  his 
isystem,  being  discoverable  in  the  deduction  of  the  cate- 
gories from  the  original  "  unity  of  apperception."  Fichte  is, 
perhaps,  not  always  quite  consistent,  since  he  sometimes, 


288  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  n. 

especially  in  his  later  writings,  seems  to  identify  his 
primordial  activity  with  a  mere  alogical  impulse ;  but 
nevertheless  his  sheet-anchor  is,  as  he  repeatedly  insists, 
self-consciousness — the  formal  unity,  the  "I  think" — of 
Kant.  Fichte,  in  other  words,  starts  with  a  formal 
principle  ;  with  him  /or-itself-ness  is  practically  ultimate, 
and  includes  m-itself-ness ;  concrete  reality  is  thus  dedu- 
cible  from  the  formal  activity  of  thouiiht  alone,  the  "  I  '* 
is  confounded  or  identified  with  the  "  think." 

It  is  not  proposed  to  pursue  the  subject  further  now, 
inasmuch  as  we  shall  have  to  recur  to  it  again  in  treating 
of  Hegel,  in  whom  we  find  the  principle  fully  and  con- 
sistently carried  out.  We  shall  then  endeavour  to  show  its 
inevitable  effect,  as  it  appears  to  us,  in  the  working  out 
of  the  speculative  method.  Our  only  object  in  mentioning 
it  here  is  to  point  out  the  position  occupied  by  the  line 
of  thought,  of  which  Schopenhauer  and  Herbart  represent 
the  two  opposite  poles,  and  which  is  based  on  the  Transcen- 
dental ^Esthetic.  With  these  schools,  the  Alogical,  whether 
as  impulse  (will)  or  feeling,  constitutes  the  prius  of  ex- 
perience. Schopenhauer  analyses  experience  into  the 
momenta  of  an  impersonal  all-determining  Will;  Herbart 
into  discrete  self-centered  units  of  feeling.  For  the  one, 
Eeality  is  a  continuous  whole  ;  for  the  other,  a  congeries,  so 
to  speak,  of  separate  points ;  the  basis  of  the  one  is 
Monistic,  that  of  the  other  Pluralistic.  Both  these  schools 
alike  reject  the  sj^eculative  method,  as  is  only  natural, 
considering  that  they  found  on  the  "Esthetic"  side  of 
the  "  critical  philosophy."  The  idea  which  is  confusedly 
present  in  Schelling's  system  is  distinctly  formulated  by 
Schopenhauer.  Schelling  sought  for  a  principle  other 
than  thought,  and  imagined  he  had  found  it  in  the  phrase 
"  Absolute  Identity,"  or  "  Indifference."  Schopenhauer 
asserted  that  the  principle  other  than  thought — the  matter 
of  which  thought  was  the  form — was  Will  undetermined 
by  any  specific  content.  Schellinoj  seems  to  have  a 
confused  consciousness  of  what  is  lacking  in  Fichte  when 
he  charges  him  with  subjectivism,  a  defect  he  evidently 
thinks  his  principle  of  "  indiffei  eiice  "  supplies.  Schelling's 
grasp  of  the  speculative  method  was,  however,  so  weak, 
especially  in  the  later  \^ritings,  that  he  has  little 
importance  in  this  connyciiun. 


Epoch  II.]  SCHOPENHAUER.  289 


SCHOPENHAUER. 

Arthur  Schopenhauer,  the  founder  of  Modern  ressiniism, 
was  born  22nd  February,  1788,  at  Dantzig.  His  father, 
a  successful  merchant  in  the  old  Hanseatio  town,  was  a 
great  traveller  for  those  dsijs,  besides  being  a  man  of 
considerable  culture.  The  wandering  life  of  his  youth 
was  doubtless  not  without  its  influence  in  the  formation 
of  young  Schopenhauer's  character.  He  resided  for  some 
time  both  in  France  and  England,  the  pietism  of  the 
latter  country  proving  particularly  obnoxious  to  him. 
Early  in  1805  Schopenhauer  entered  a  merchant's  office, 
where  he  remained,  much  against  his  inclinations,  for 
twelve  months ;  after  which,  his  father  ha^^ng  died  in  the 
meantime  in  consequence  of  an  accident,  he  entered  the 
university  of  Gotha,  with  the  intention  of  devoting 
himself  to  literature.  He  subsequently  left  Gotha  for 
Weimar,  then  at  the  zenith  of  its  literary  splendour,  his 
own  mother,  Johanna  Schopenhauer,  the  novelist,  being  a 
j^rominent  figure  there.  In  1807  he  repaired  to  Gottingen, 
where  he  matriculated  in  the  medical  faculty.  Alter 
some  further  travelling,  in  the  course  of  which  he  visited 
Italy,  he  finally  settled  down  at  Frankfort-on-the-Maine, 
where  he  remained,  with  but  little  intermission,  until  his 
death  on  September  21st,  1860,  and  where  most  of  his 
works  were  written. 

Schopenhauer,  though  not  so  voluminous  a  writer  as 
Fichte  or  Schelling,  possesses  a  literary  charm,  wanting  in 
all  other  German  philosophers.  He  was  an  ardent 
student  of  those  remarkable  products  of  Oriental  thought, 
the  Upanischads,  and  it  is  to  these,  conjoined  with  Kant, 
that  his  conception  of  a  systematic  Pessimism  must  be 
immediately  traced.  Schopenhauer's  chief  work  is  his 
'  World  as  Will  and  Presentation.'  He  is  also  the  author 
of  a  treatise,  '  On  the  fourfold  Eoot  of  the  principle  of 
adequate  cause '  (his  first  work),  of  two  charming  volumes 
of  miscellaneous  essays  to  which  he  gave  the  name  of 
*  Parerga  and  Paralipomena,'  of  a  treatise  on  '  Will  in 
Nature,'  and  other  less  important  pieces. 

u 


290  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 


Philosophy  of   Schopenhauer. 

In  his  earliest  work,  '  The  Fourfold  Eoot,'  Schopen- 
hauer takes  his  stand  on  Kant's  reduction  of  space  and 
time  to  subjective  forms.  He,  however,  blames  Kant  for 
having  assumed  twelve  categories  where  one  only,  that  of 
Causality,  is  necessary.  He  also  criticises  Kant's  sepa- 
ration of  perception  from  thought,  since  space  and  time 
themselves  are  but  one  of  the  four  forms  of  the  principle 
of  causation  which  is  as  much  sensuous  as  intellectual. 
The  four  forms  of  the  principle  of  causality,  in  question, 
are  termed  by  Schopenhauer  respectively  the  ratio  essencU, 
Jiendi,  agendi,  et  cognoscendi.  The  two  first  forms  are 
constructive  of  the  object  itself.  The  ratio  essendi  is 
nothing  other  than  the  space  and  time  form  of  the  inner 
and  outer  sense— succession  and  co-existence.  The  ratio 
fieiidi  is  the  relation  of  things  as  cause  and  effect, 
properly  so  called.  By  this  relation,  causality  con- 
stitutes the  object  in  time  and  space,  real.  Through 
causality  alone  can  it  become  object;  hence  the  notion 
of  an  object  apart  from  the  relation  implied  in  causality 
(e.g.  a  first-cause)  is  a  contradiction  in  terms.  The 
three  chief  phases  of  cause-and-effect  are  mechanical 
impact  (inorganic),  irritability  or  reflex  action  (organic), 
and  motive  (psychic).  Every  change  of  state  pre-supposes 
a  prior  state;  hence  the  absurdity  of  the  assumptions  of 
Theism.  Matter  is  the  only  reality,  inasmuch  as  a  timed, 
spaced,  and  caused  object,  must  necessarily  be  material. 
The  ratio  jiendi  of  Schopenhauer,  unlike  Kant's  category 
of  cause  and  effect,  is  not,  as  it  were,  thought  into  the  object 
by  the  understanding  ;  the  causal  relations  proper,  of  the 
latter,  are  as  much  intuited  as  its  time  and  space  relations. 
The  third  principle,  the  ratio  cognoscendi,  is  not,  like  the 
two  former,  constructive  of  the  object,  i.e.  not  creative  ;  it 
is  the  faculty  of  discursive  thought,  which  by  Kant,  Fichte, 
Schelling,  and  their  school,  has  been  falsely,  under  the 
name  of  the  "  Eeason,"  given  a  pre-eminence  over  those 
principles  which  go  to  the  construction  of  the  real.  The 
ratio  cognoscendi  is,  in  short,  merely  the  faculty  of  forming 
abstract  conceptions.     The  fourth  form  of  the  principle  of 


Epoch  II.]  SCHOPENHAUER.  291 

Cause,  the  ratio  agendi,  shows  us  the  principle  as  deter- 
mined from  within,  but  none  the  less  7?<?cess«n7// determined, 
in  other  words  as  indirifJual  icill  or  motivation.  To  sum 
up  :  the  principle  of  Cause  in  its  four  forms,  interpenetrates 
the  world,  but  inasmuch  as  it  is  only  a  principle  belonging 
to  our  faculty  of  presentation,  it  follows  that  the  world 
itself  is  nothing  but  our  presentation.  The  Ego  itself  is 
but  phenomenal,  and  appears  as  individual  in  so  far 
as  it  is  an  object  in  time  and  space,  since  they  may  be 
called  the  pincipia  individuationis.  My  body  lias  as  much 
right  to  the  appellation  microcosmos  as  the  universe  has 
to  the  appellation  maJcanfhropos. 

The  foregoing  exposition,  which  is  contained  in  '  The 
Fourfold  Root,'  may  be  regarded,  taken  by  itself,  as  little 
more  than  a  rectified  Kantism.  This  view  is  modified 
directly  the  main  position  of  Schopenhauer  is  taken  into 
consideration.  Schopenhauer's  philosophy  does  not  rest 
satisfied  with  an  analysis  of  the  world  as  phenomenon, 
that  is,  as  subordinated  to  the  principle  of  causation.  It 
claims  to  have  a  word  to  say  on  the  world  regarded  as 
thing-in-itself,  as  noumenon.  The  immediate  investiga- 
tion into  the  nature  of  experience  discloses  a  something 
which  we  call  world,  appearing  under  divers  forms,  all  of 
which  may  ultimately  be  regarded  as  modes  of  causation. 
But  what  is  this  thing  which  appeals,  which  becomes 
object  of  consciousness — what  is  the  thing,  that  is  con- 
sidered fipart  from  its  appearance  ?  Schopenhauer's  answer 
is,  that  wliicli  appears  is  not  consciousness,  for  the  latter, 
pursue  it  as  far  back  as  you  may,  still  remains  only  the 
form  assumed  by  the  thing  itself;  this,  the  matter  of  the 
world,  is  not  conscious  but  a-conscious,  not  Intellect  but 
Will. 

'•  The  idea  of  the  soul  as  a  metaphysical  being,"  says 
Schopenhauer,  "in  whose  absolute  simplicity  will  and 
intellect  were  an  indissoluble  unity,  was  a  great  and 
permanent  impediment  to  all  deeper  insight  into  natural 
phenomena.  The  cardinal  merit  of  my  doctrine,  and  that 
which  puts  it  in  opposition  to  all  former  philosophies, 
is  the  perfect  separation  of  the  will  from  the  intellect. 
All  former  philosophers  thought  will  to  be  inseparable 
from  intellect ;  the  will  was  declared  to  be   conditioned 

u  2 


292  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

by  the  intellect,  or  even  to  be  a  mere  function  of  it, 
whilst  the  intellect  was  regarded  as  the  fundamental 
principle  of  our  spiritual  existence.  I  am  well  aware  that 
to  the  future  alone  belongs  the  recognition  of  this  doctrine, 
but  to  the  future  philosophy  the  separation,  or  rather  the 
decomposition  of  the  soul  into  two  heterogeneous  elements, 
will  have  the  same  significance  as  the  decomposition  of 
water  had  to  chemistiy.  Not  the  soul  is  the  eternal  and 
indestructible  principle  of  life  in  man,  but  what  I  might 
call  the  root  of  the  soul,  and  that  is  the  Will.  The  so- 
called  soul  is  alread}^  a  compound  ;  it  is  the  combination  of 
will  and  vovs,  intellect.  The  intellect  is  the  secondary, 
the  posterius  in  any  organism,  and,  as  a  mere  function  of 
the  brain,  dependent  upon  the  organism.  The  will,  on 
the  contrary,  is  primary,  the  prius  of  the  organism,  and 
the  organism  consequently  is  conditioned  by  it.  For  the 
will  is  the  very  '  thing-in-itself,'  which  in  conception 
(that  is,  in  the  peculiar  function  of  the  brain)  exhibits 
itself  as  an  organic  body.  Only  by  virtue  of  the  forms  of 
cognition,  that  is,  by  virtue  of  that  function  of  the  brain — 
hence  only  in  conception — is  one's  body  something  ex- 
tended and  organic,  and  not  apart  therefrom  or  immedi- 
ately in  self-consciousness.  Just  as  the  various  single 
acts  of  the  body  are  nothing  but  the  various  acts  of  the 
will  portrayed  in  the  represented  world,  so  is  the  shape 
of  this  body  as  a  totality,  the  image  of  its  will  as  a  whole. 
In  all  organic  functions  of  the  body,  therefore,  just  as  in  its 
external  actions,  the  \^ill  is  the  '  agens.'  True  physiology 
shows  the  intellect  to  be  the  product  of  the  phj^sical 
organisation,  but  true  metaphysics  show,  that  physical 
existence  itself  is  the  product,  or  rather  the  appearance, 
of  a  spiritual  agens,  to  wit,  the  will ;  nay,  that  matter 
itself  is  conditioned  through  conception,  in  which  alone  it 
exists.  Perception  and  thought  may  well  be  explained  by 
the  nature  of  the  organism ;  the  will  never  can  be ;  the 
contrary  is  true,  namely,  that  every  organism  originates 
by  and  from  the  will."  ( JJeher  den  Willen  in  der  Natur, 
2nd  edition,  185-i,  Frankfcrt,  pp.  19-20.)  The  foregoing 
quotation  may  fairly  be  taken  as  a  succinct  epitome  of 
the  more  purely  metaphysical  side  of  Schopenhauer's 
philosophy. 


Epoch  IL]  SCHOPENHAUER.  203 

Our  consciousness  of  ourself  is  a  consciousness  of  ourself 
as  object;  that  which  becomes  consciousness  of  itself,  in 
other  words,  the  in-itselfness  of  the  world,  and  a  fortiori, 
of  ourselves  as  individuals,  is  nothing  other  than  that 
element  of  our  nature  which  we  term  Will.  By  the  word 
Will,  in  Schopenhauer's  sense,  is  to  he  understood  all 
impulse  whatsoever,  mechanical,  physical,  chemical,  no 
less  than  organic  and  psychic.  It  is  the  same  impulse 
which  is  manifested  in  gravitation,  in  magnetism, 
which  expresses  itself  in  the  growth  of  the  plant,  in 
the,  reproduction  and  development  of  the  animal,  and 
in  the  will  of  man.  Why,  then,  it  may  be  Hsked,  does 
Schopenhauer  emplo}^  the  word  ivill  rather  than  force 
to  designate  this  in-itselfness,  this  infinite  potentiality 
of  the  world  ?  His  reply  is,  that  he  designates  it  by  the 
term  connoting  its  highest  expression  (as  it  is  immedi- 
ately known  to  us) ;  ivill  is  known  immediately,  force 
mediately  only.  "  The  distance,"  observed  Schopen- 
hauer, "the  indeed,  in  appearance,  comj^lete  diversity 
between  the  phenomenon  of  inorganic  nature,  and  that 
Will  which  we  perceive  to  be  the  inmost  nature  of  our 
own  being,  arises  mainly  from  the  contrast  between  the 
fully  determined  regularity  of  the  one,  and  the  apparently 
lawless  independence  of  the  other  class  of  phenomena. 
For  in  man  the  individuality  comes  strongly  to  the  fore ; 
each  has  a  special  character,  hence  the  same  motive  has 
not  the  same  power  over  all,  and  there  are  thousands  of 
surrounding  circumstances  having  their  place  in  the  wide 
sphere  of  individual  knowledge,  but  remaining  unknown 
to  others,  which  modify  its  effect ;  for  this  reason  the 
action  cannot  be  predicted  from  the  motive  alone,  inas- 
much as  the  other  factor  is  wanting,  namely,  the  exact 
acquaintance  with  the  individual  character  and  the 
knowledge  accompanyiug  it.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
phenomena  of  natural  forces  exhibits  the  opposj^ite  extreme  ; 
they  act  according  to  universal  laws,  without  deviation, 
without  individuality,  in  accordance  with  obvious  circum- 
stances, and  are  capable  of  the  most  precise  prevision,  the 
same  natural  force  manifesting  itself  in  millions  of 
phenomena  precisely  in  the  same  wa.y  "  ( Welt  ah  Wille, 
voh  i.  pp.  134-5), 


294  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

The  most   immediate  objectivation  of  the  will  is  the 
organism   or  body.     For   the  Subject  of  knowledge  the 
body  is  given   in  a  twofold  way,   as  an  object  amongst 
objects,  biibject  to  the  laws  of  matter,  and  as  the  direct 
embodiment  of  Will.     The  act  of  the  will  and  the  act  of 
the  body  are  not  two  things  bound  together  by  a  causal 
nexus, — the  action  of  the  body  does  not  foUoio  the  action 
of  the  will,  as   an   effect  follows  a   cause — but   the  two 
states  are  the  same  fact  differently  viewed,  in  other  words, 
as  above  stated,  the  body  is  the  immediate  objectivation 
of  the  will.      The   question   as   to  the  existence  of  the 
external  world  resolves  itself,  when  closely  viewed,  into 
the  question  whether  the  objects  known  to  the  individual 
merely  as  such,  that  is,  merely  as  presentati<  ms,  are,  like 
his  own  body,  manifestations  of  Will.     We  are  justified, 
according  to  Schopenhauer,  in  applying  the  analogy  of 
the  object,    our   own   body,  which,  as   we  have   said,  is 
manifested    in    a    double   way,   to   other   objects   which 
are  not  so  manifested.     They  agree  with  it  in  that  they 
are  phenomena  of  consciousness.     Let  us  abstract  from 
this  aspect  of  them,  and  they  remain  either  nothing  at 
all,  as  the  subjective  idealist  affirms  (an  assertion  which  is 
obviously  a  reductio  ad  ahsurdum),  or  else  they  must  be  of 
the  same  nature  with  that  which  in  ourselves  we  term 
will.     As  in  man  that  which  determines  character  is  will, 
so  the    quality   which  distinguishes  things,   which   gives 
them   their  specific  character,  consists  in   the  particular 
stage  in  the  objectivation  of  the  will  which  they  represent. 
The  will,  as  manifested  in  time  and  space  and  subject  to 
cause,  appears  in  an  infinity  of  individuals,  for  time  and 
space  are  the  principles  of  individuation.      In  itself,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  Will  is  absolutely  one  and  indivisible. 
Between  the  will  as  thing-in-itself,  and  the  will  as  indi- 
vidualised in  space  and  time,  we  have  to  consider  the  will 
as  expressed   in   the  several   stages   of  its  objectivation. 
These  stages  of  the  objectivation  of  the  will  correspond  to 
the  ideas  of  Plato.    They  are  the  eternal  changeless  forms, 
the   permanent   entia,   of  which   the   evanescent  flux   of 
individuals  partakes,  and  by  which  they  are  more  or  less 
imperfectly  expressed.     This  doctrine  furnishes  the  basis 
for  Schopenhauer's  theorj'  of   Art,  just    as   the  doctrine 


Epoch  II.]  SCHOPENHAUER.  295 

of  tlie  Will  (or  as  Schopenhauer  sometimes  terms  it  tlie 
"  will- to-live  "),  as  thing -iu-itself  furnishes  the  basis  for 
his  theory  of  Ethics. 

We  have  already  seen  that  the  will  as  thing-in-itself 
is  opposed  to  the  Will  as  phenomenon  or  object  of  con- 
sciousness, as  which  it  tends  to  lose  its  essential  cha- 
racter. The  essence  of  will  consists  in  activity,  in  a 
striving  after  something  unattained.  The  essence  of 
intelligence  or  understanding,  as  Schopenhauer  terms 
it,  that  is,  of  completed  consciousness,  consists,  on  the 
other  hand,  in  passivity — in  the  contemplation  of  an 
object  as  given.  In  ordinary  Empirical  consciousness, 
however,  which  takes  place  under  the  forms  of  time  and 
space,  the  two  aspects,  that  of  the  world  as  will,  and  the 
world  as  perception  appear,  together.  It  is  only  in  the 
art-product,  in  the  gesthetic  consciousness,  that  intelligence 
or  perception  is  to  be  found  pure  and  undisturbed  by  the 
restless  striving  of  Will.  First  of  all  let  us  hear 
Schopenhauer  on  the  essential  nature  of  Will.  "  All 
willing,"  he  says,  "  arises  from  desire,  that  is  from  want, 
that  is  from  snifering.  Satisfaction  makes  an  end  of  this ; 
but  nevertheless,  for  every  wish  that  is  gratified,  there 
remain  at  least  ten  unfulfilled.  Furthermore,  desire  lasts 
long ;  its  yearnings  are  infinite,  while  satisfaction  is 
short,  and  sparingly  measured  out.  But  even  the  satis- 
faction is  only  illusory ;  the  gratified  wish  at  once  gives 
place  to  a  new  one ;  the  former  is  a  recognised,  the  latter 
a  still  unrecognised,  mistake.  Lasting,  unfading  satis- 
faction, no  desired  object  of  the  will  can  afi'ord  ;  it  is  like 
the  alms  thrown  to  the  beggar,  which  prolong  his  life  for 
the  day,  only  to  postpone  his  suffering  till  the  morrow. 
So  long,  therefore,  as  our  consciousness  is  absorbed  in  our 
will,  so  long  are  we  given  up  to  the  stress  of  wishes  with 
its  continuous  hoping  and  fearing  ;  so  long  as  we  are  the 
subject  of  will,  lasting  happiness  or  rest  will  never  be  our 
lot.  Whether  we  pursue  or  flee,  dread  evil  or  strive  after 
pleasure,  is  essentially  the  same,  the  care  for  an  ever  onward 
urging  will,  it  matters  not  what  be  its  shape,  ceaselessly 
moves  and  fills  the  consciousness;  but  without  rest  no 
true  happiness  is  possible.  Thus  is  the  subject  of  the  will 
bound  eternally  on  the  revolving  wheel  of  Ixion,  thus 


296  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

does  it  ceaselessly  gather  in  the  sieve  of  the  Danaids,  thus, 
like  Tantalus,  is  it  ever  languishing "  ( Welt  als  Willey 
vol.  i.,  §  38).  In  this  fine  passage  the  Pessimistic  doctrine 
is  admirably  expressed.  Schopenhauer's  pessimism  is 
something  more  than  empirical  pessimism.  It  claims  a 
character  of  a  priori  certainty.  The  absolute  Will,  in 
sundering  itself  into  I  and  not  I,  entered  a  fiery  ordeal 
which  can  only  be  terminated  by  the  negation  of  the  loill 
to  live,  but  of  this  more  anon.  To  the  common  mind 
pleasure  is  positive,  and  pain  negative.  For  Schopenhauer 
this  is  an  illusion,  the  reverse  being  the  truth.  Pain  is 
the  positive,  and  pleasure  the  negative.  Pleasure  being 
nothing  more  than  the  cessation  of  a  pain,  or  the  satisfac- 
tion of  a  want,  consequent  on  which  new  pains  or  new 
wants  obtrude  themselves.  In  short,  since  all  Will  implies 
action,  all  action  want,  all  want  pain,  it  follows  that  pain 
and  misery  are  the  essential  condition  of  Will,  and  of  that 
ordinary  empirical  consciousness  into  which  Will  enters, 
i.e.  the  consciousness  which  is  subordinated  to  space,  time 
and  cause,  and  which  constitutes  the  illusory  world  of 
multiplicity  and  individuation — the  veil  of  the  Maya,  to 
employ  the  language  of  the  Upanischads.  But  as  before 
said,  there  is  another  kind  of  consciousness  which  is  pure 
and  free  from  any  admixture  with  Will  as  such. 

It  is  this  consciousness  which  contemplates  the  stages  of 
the  Will's  objectivation  in  their  pure  form  and  not  as  dis- 
torted by  the  time  and  space  world  of  individual  things. 
In  this  aesthetic  contemplation  the  Will  becomes  more  or  lei?s 
completely  dominated  by,  or,  we  may  rather  say,  metamor- 
phosed into,  "  presentation  '\Vorstellung),  the  latter  in  this 
case  not  being,  as  in  ordinary  consciousness,  merely  "  the 
servant  of  the  W^ill."  The  third  book  of  Schopen- 
hauer's Welt  als  Wille  und  Vorstellung,  is  occupied  with  a 
discussion  on  the  place  occupied  by  the  several  depart- 
ments of  the  fine  Arts  in  the  presentment  of  the  Will's 
objectivation.  The  idea,  although  not  subject  to  the 
various  forms  of  the  principle  of  causality,  bears  never- 
theless the  most  universal  characteristic  of  knowledge  or 
presentment,  that  of  being  an  object  for  a  subject.  As 
individuals,  we  have  no  knowledge  but  such  as  is  involved 
in  causation,  and  from  the  knowledge  of  individual  things 


Erocii  II.]  SCHOPENHAUER.  297 

we  can  only  raise  ourselves  to  the  knowledge  of  the  ideas 
by  virtue  of  a  change  in  our  cognitive  nature,  by  which, 
from  being  individual  it  becomes  universal.  The  natural 
state  wherein  consciousness  or  perception  is  at  the  service 
of  the  Will  is  in  the  case  of  animals  not  to  be  transcended. 
Man  alone  can  attain  to  a  knowledge  of  the  idea  in  so  far 
as  his  consciousness  severs  itself  from  its  natural  obedience 
to  the  Will.  In  the  fixed  contemplation  of  the  object  in 
its  intrinsic  nature,  the  Why,  the  Wherefore,  and  the  When 
of  things  is  neglected ;  their  Wliatness,  their  quality,  is 
alone  considered,  not  in  discursive  thought  but  in  imme- 
diate perception.  This  peculiar  mode  of  cognition  is  the 
foundation  of  Art;  in  the  Art-work  the  idea  seized  in 
this  act  of  contemplation,  is  reproduced  under  the  forms 
of  empirical  consciousness.  The  aim  of  Art  is  the  pre- 
sentment of  these  ideas,  which  are  the  essential  and 
permanent  in  all  the  phenomena  of  the  world.  What  is 
the  process  by  which  the  creations  of  Art  are  produced  ? 
asks  Schopenhauer.  "  It  is  suj^posed  by  the  imitation  of 
Nature ;  but  wherein  shall  the  Artist  recognise  the  success- 
ful in  her  and  the  work  which  is  to  be  imitated,  and  pick 
it  out  from  among  her  abortive  attempts,  if  he  do  not 
anticipate  the  Beautiful  pior  to  experience  f*  Besides,  has 
Nature  ever  furnished  a  human  being  perfectly  beautiful 
in  every  respect  ?  It  has  been  supposed  that  the  Artist 
must  gather  together  the  beautiful  sides  of  many  indi- 
vidual human  beings,  and  out  of  these  piece  together  a 
beautiful  whole,  a  false  and  foolish  opinion  !  For  we  ask 
again,  How  shall  we  know  that  precisely  these  forms  are 
beautiful  and  those  not  ?  *  *  *  Purely  a  'posteriori  and 
through  mere  experience  no  knowledge  of  the  Beautiful 
is  possible ;  it  is  always  at  least  in  part  a  priori,  although 
of  course,  in  a  different  sense  to  the  forms  of  the  principle 
of  cause  of  which  we  are  also  conscious  a  priori." 

The  idea  as  such,which  the  Art-work  reproduces,  is  apart 
from  space,  time  and  individuation,  but  its  reproduction 
through  a  sensuous  medium  shows  various  gradations 
represented  by  the  various  Arts.  In  Music  we  have  the 
purest  and  most  immediate  reproduction  of  the  idea ;  in 
all  the  other  Arts,  notabl3'-  Sculpture  and  Painting,  this 
takes  place  through  special  archetypal  forms,  the  Platonic 


298  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

ideas  proper,  but  in  Music  without  the  intervention  of 
any  special  form.  "  After  having,"  says  Schopenhauer, 
*'  considered  in  the  foregoing  all  the  tine  Arts  in  that 
universality  which  our  standpoint  demands,  beginning 
from  Architecture,  whose  end,  as  such,  is  to  render  clear 
the  objectivation  of  the  Will  at  the  lowest  stage  of  its 
manifestation,  where  it  appears  as  dull,  unconscious, 
determinate  impulse  of  the  mass — though  even  here  reveal- 
ing differentiation  and  struggle,  to  wit,  as  between  giaviiy 
and  fixity — and  closing  our  consideration  with  the  tragedy, 
which,  at  the  highest  stage  of  the  objectivation  of  the 
Will,  exhibits  its  conflict  with  itself  in  fearful  magni- 
tude and  clearness,  we  find  there  is  still  one  of  the  tine 
Arts  which  has  of  necessity  been  excluded  from  our  inves- 
tigation, since  there  was  no  place  for  it  in  the  systematic 
connection  of  our  exposition  ;  it  is  Music.  It  stands  apart 
from  all  others  *  *  *  The  Ideas  are  the  adequate  objectiva- 
tion of  the  Will ;  to  excite  the  knowledge  of  these  through 
the  presentation  of  individual  things  is  the  end  of  all  the 
Arts.  They  all  objectivise  the  AVill  mediately,  namely, 
through  the  Ideas,  our  world  being  nothing  but  the 
phenomenon  of  the  Ideas  in  plurality,  by  means  of  the 
principium  individuationis  which  is  the  only  possible  form 
of  knowledge  for  the  individual.  Music,  on  the  other 
hand,  inasmuch  as  it  transcends  the  Ideas,  is  completely 
independent  of  the  phenomenal  world,  ignores  it  entirely, 
and  could,  in  a  sense,  exist,  even  though  the  world  were 
not,  which  cannot  be  said  of  the  other  Arts.  Music  is, 
therefore,  as  immediate  an  objectivation  and  reflection  of 
the  Will  as  is  the  \\  orld  itself ;  or  as  are  the  Ideas,  whose 
manifold  phenomenon  the  world  of  individual  things,  is. 
Music  is  thus  in  no  wise  like  the  other  Arts,  the  copy  of 
the  Ideas,  but  the  copy  of  the  Will  itself,  whose  objectivity 
the  Ideas  are.  For  this  reason  the  eff'ect  of  Music  is  so 
mnch  more  powerful  and  impressive  than  that  of  the 
other  Arts,  for  while  they  speak  only  of  shadows,  it  speaks 
of  substance."  (Welt  ah  'Wille,  vol.  i.,  §  52.) 

The  delight  afforded  by  the  Beautiful,  the  joys  of  Art, 
the  enthusiasm  of  the  Artist,  all  turn  upon  the  fact,  that 
in  Art  the  striving  of  the  Will  is  temporarily  stilled.  In 
aisthetic  contemplation  we  cease  to  will,  we  become  purely 


Epoch  II.]  SCHOPENHAUER.  299 

passive,  we  cognise  merel3\  But  Art,  though  a  quietude  of 
the  Will,  does  not  deliver  it  for  ever,  but  only  during 
moments  of  life,  and  i«  therefore  not  the  way  out  of  the 
struggle,  Init  at  Lest,  a  temporary  consolation  within  it. 
The  liiial  deliverance  which  constitutes  the  main  proljleni 
of  the  Ethical  side  of  Schopenhauer's  philosophy,  is  dealt 
with  by  him  in  the  fuurtli  book  of  the  Welt  als  Wille. 
The  Will-to-live  which  involves  a  ceaseless  strife,  a  never- 
ending  eifort  to  attain  the  unattainable,  and  therefore  an 
ever-present  sufltering,  may  be,  according  to  Schopenhauer, 
either  affirmed  or  denied.  Jts  affirmation  takes  place 
when  the  individual  surrenders  himself  to  the  Will  which 
is  objectivised  in  him,  by  obeying  his  natural  impulses 
tending  to  the  preservation  of  himself  and  the  reproduc- 
tion of  the  species.  It  is  denied,  when  the  Will-to-live — 
not  necessarily  life  itself,*  but  the  desires  which  minister 
to  the  preservation  and  rejjroduction  of  life — are  ex- 
tinguished within  him.  The  basis  of  all  practical  morality 
is  sympathy  with  the  suffering  inseparable  from  life,  a 
sympathy  which  is  the  outcome  of  the  consciousness,  vague 
or  clear,  of  the  ultimate  identity  of  our  own  Will  with  the 
AVill  of  all  other  sentient  beings.  The  Ideal  goal  of 
Ethics  is  the  final  negation  of  the  Will-to-live,  the  way  to 
which  is  to  be  found  in  asceticism.  Consciousness,  the 
last  phase  of  the  Will,  must  be  played  out  before  the 
end  can  come.  Not  until  all  desire  is  extinguished  in 
case  deliverance  finally  be  accomplished.  Schopenhauer 
naturally  found  the  type  of  his  asceticism  in  the  Buddhist 
monk,  and  to  a  somewhat  less  extent  in  the  Trappist. 
"  In  this  way,"  concludes  Schopenhauer,  "  in  the  con- 
templation of  the  life  and  career  of  the  saints  to  meet 
with  Avhom  is  seldom  granted  to  one's  own  experience, 
but  of  which  their  written  history  assures  us  with  the 
impress  of  inner  truth  that  is  upon  it,  and  which  Art 
brings  before  our  eyes,  we  have  the  dark  impression  of 
that  nothingness  that  looms  as  the  final  goal  behind  all 
virtue  and  holiness,  and  which  we  dread  as  children 
dread  the  darkness.    Instead  of,  like  the  Hindoos,  seeking 

*  Suicide  Schopenhauer  regarded  as  a  clumsy  solution  of  the  prob- 
lem, since  the  will  is  not  thereby  destroyed,  but  only,  so  to  speak, 
temporarily  inverted. 


300  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

to  evade  it  througli  mytHs  and  meaningless  words,  such 
as  reabsorption  in  the  world-soul,  or  the  Buddhist  Nir- 
vana, let  us  rather  confess  freely  that  after  the  complete 
destruction  of  the  Will,  what  remains  is,  for  all  those  who 
are  still  immersed  in  the  AVill,  assuredly  nothingness. 
But  on  the  other  hand,  for  those  in  whom  the  Will  has 
already  turned  against  and  denied  itself,  this  our  so  very 
real  world,  with  all  its  suns  and  galaxies,  is  also  nothing- 
ness." (Welt  ah  Wille,  vol.  i.,  §  17.) 

In  spite  of  the  abuse  and  ridicule  which  Schopenhauer 
heaped  upon  the  Guild-philosophers,  as  he  termed  Fichte, 
Schelling  and  Hegel,  there  is  very  little  in  his  system 
which  is  not  discoverable  incidentally  at  least  in  the  works 
of  the  two  former  thinkers.  With  Fichte,  of  course,  self- 
consciousness  was  a  starting-point,  but  the  self-conscious 
Ego  reappears  later  on  in  the  system  as  moral  impulse, 
which  for  Fichte,  as  for  Schopenhauer,  consists  in  the 
negation  of  the  phenomenal  world  through  Asceticism. 
Schopenhauer  is,  of  course,  far  more  logical  in  this 
respect  than  even  Fichte,  who  does  not  carry  the  principle 
of  asceticism  to  its  final  issue  of  self-starvation,  like  the 
pessimist  writer.  In  Schelling,  again,  the  conception  of 
Will  as  prius  is  clearly  traceable.  Schopenhauer's  chief 
merit  lies  in  the  clearness  and  consistency  with  which  he 
carries  out  positions  which  had  heretofore  been  either 
imperfectly  developed  or  tlirown  out  more  in  the  form  of 
suggestion  than  of  positive  theory.  The  prominence 
Schopenhauer  gives  to  the  distinction  between  the  Alo- 
gical  or  Material  and  the  logical  or  formal  element  in 
experience,  to  which  we  have  already  alluded,  is  the  most 
original  feature  of  the  purely  metaphysical  side  of  his 
doctrine,  and  may  be  undoubtedly  traced  to  a  reaction 
against  the  formalism  of  Hegel.  Schopenhauer  has  the 
merit  of  being  the  first  philosopher  in  modern  times,  if  we 
except  some  of  the  French  materialists,  who  is  honest 
enough  to  refrain  from  the  usual  lip-homage  to  the  domi- 
nant creed.  His  "  Free-thought "  is,  indeed,  in  some 
instance,  decidedly  aggressive.  He  steadily  refused  to 
employ  theological  terminology  in  a  sense  misleading  even 
to  the  '*  vulgar."  He  did  not,  as  many  would  have  done, 
import  the  term  "  God  "  (innocent  little  word,  the  friend 


Epoch  II.]  HERBART.  301 

in  need  of  speculative  time-servers)  into  his  system, 
well  knowing  that  the  notions  it  implied  were  foreign 
thereto.  His  polemic  against  Theism  extends  even  to  the 
term  "  pantheism,"  which  he  stigmatises  as  involving  a 
meaningless  use  of  language. 

For  a  long  time  Schopenhauer  remained  entirely  un- 
recognised. Towards  the  close  of  his  life,  however,  a 
circle  of  devoted  admirers  began  to  form  around  him. 
Chief  among  these  were  his  biographer,  Dr.  Gwinner,  and 
his  editor  and  annotator,  Dr.  Frauenstadt,  both  enthusiastic 
disciples.  The  subsequent  development  of  the  pessimist 
doctrine  in  Germany,  we  shall  deal  with  briefly  later  on. 


HERBART. 

JoHANN  Friedrich  Herbart  was  bom  May  4th,  1776  at 
Oldenburg,  where  his  father  occupied  an  official  position; 
Originally  educated  in  the  Leibnitz-Wolffian  school,  he 
soon  turned  to  Kant.  In  1794,  he  attended  Fichte's 
lectures  at  Jena,  and  at  this  period  he  began  to  write 
essays  criticizing  Fichte  and  Schelling.  On  leaving  the 
university  he  entered  a  Swiss  family,  as  private  tutor, 
about  the  same  time  making  the  acquaintance  of  the 
educationalist  Pestalozzi,  whose  theories  he  warmly  cham- 
pioned. In  1802  Herbart  became  lecturer  in  philosophy 
at  the  university  of  Gottingen,  where  he  remained  until 
1809,  when  Wilhelm  von  Humbolt  procured  him  the 
professorship  of  philosophy  at  Konigsberg,  just  then 
vacant.  In  Konigsberg  he  instituted  a  "  pedagogic " 
seminary  which  he  himself  directed.  Herbart  returned 
in  1833  to  Gottingen  as  professor,  remaining  there  in 
uninterrupted  activity  till  his  death  on  August  4th, 
1841.  Herbart's  works  were  published  after  his  death,  in 
twelve  volumes,  by  his  pupil  Hartenstein  (Leipzig, 
1850-52). 


302         •  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 


Herbart's  Philosophy. 

Herbart  frequently  professes  to  be  a  follower  of  Kant, 
but  adds  he  is  a  Kantian  of  the  year  1828,  who  rejects  the 
entire  Idealistic  side  of  the  critical  doctrine.  Under  these 
circumstances  it  is  difficult  at  the  first  glance  to  see  how 
he  could  have  retained  anything  that  was  distinctive  of 
the  system  ;  nevertheless,  the  fact  remains  that  he  was 
influenced  by  Kantism,  altliough  rejecting  its  salient 
features.  Herbart  took  his  stand  on  Kant's  distinction 
between  phenomena  and  things-in-themselves,  between  the 
sense-presentation  and  the  hypothetic  cause  of  the.  sense- 
presentation.  But  while  the  thing-in-itself,  the  external 
cause  of  the  sense-impression,  was  to  Kant  unkno\vn, 
Herbart  professed  to  be  able  to  penetrate  the  phenomenon 
and  give  some  account  of  the  producing  noumenon.  Herbart 
may  thus  to  a  certain  extent  be  regarded  as  a  reaction  in 
favour  of  the  old  dogmatism  which  Kant  had  expressly 
combated.  All  philosoph}^  according  to  Herbart,  proceeds 
from  a  reflection  on  psychological  data.  He  somewhere 
calls  philosophy  "  the  working  out  of  conceptions,"  but 
this  working  out  difi'ers  to  some  extent  in  method,  in  the 
several  departments  of  philosophy.  In  Logic,  which  is  its 
vestibule,  it  is  concerned  with  rendering  conceptions  clear 
and  distinct  which  is  efi'ected  in  the  judgment.  The  two 
first  figures  of  the  Syllogism  correspond  to  the  positive  and 
negative  judgment,  and  may  be  cast  together  under  the 
name  of  the  syllogism  of  subsumption.  The  third  figure  is 
termed  by  Herbart  the  syllogism  of  substitution,  inasmuch 
as  it  is  only  valid  where  a  substitution  of  the  minor  is 
admissible.  The  great  result  furnished  by  logic  to  all  the 
departments  of  philosophy  is  the  principle  of  "  Identity, 
contradiction,  and  excluded  middle,"  in  accordance  with 
which,  conceptions  which  are  mutually  contradictory,  must 
be  rejected  and  their  opposite  accepted.  When  we  view 
conceptions  from  the  side  of  their  content,  we  find  that  they 
fall  under  tw^o  classes.  The  conceptions  b}^  virtue  of  which 
we  comprehend  the  given  world  form  one  class,  and  the 
conceptions  which  do  not  afi'ect  the  reality  of  the  thing 


Epoch  II.]  HERBART.  *  303 

couceived,  inasmuch  as  they  are  as  capable  of  a^iplication 
to  an  imaginary,  as  to  a  real  fact,  those,  namely,  of  which 
iEsthetics  and  Ethics  treat,  constitute  the  other  class. 
The  working  out  of  the  first  order  of  concepti(ms  belongs 
to  metaphysics  proper,  that  of  the  second  to  "  practical 
philosophy."  The  two  departments  are  to  be  kept  rigidly 
asunder.  Metaphysics  has  nothing  to  do  with  Ethics,  nor 
Ethics  with  Metaphysics.  Herbart  Idmself  in  the  presenta- 
tion of  his  system,  contained  in  his  "  Introductory  Manual 
of  PhiU)Sophy  "  (Lehrhuch  ziir  Einleitiing  in  die  Pliilosopliie), 
places  the  practical  side  of  his  system  before  the  theoretical 
— the  Ethics  before  the  Metaphysics— but  for  the  con- 
venience of  exposition,  we  shall  in  the  present  sketch 
follow  the  usual  order  in  this  respect,  and  give-  a  brief 
statement  of  the  metaphysics  first,  more  especially  as  the 
connection  with  Kant  and  the  posL-Kantians  is  more  easily 
seen  in  this  way.  Under  metaphysic,  Herbart,  like  W  olf, 
includes  the  whole  theoretical  side  of  philosophy.  It  is 
easy  to  see  that  the  influence  of  his  earlier  Wolffian  train- 
ing is  always  uppermost  in  Herbart.  He  is  essentially  a 
dogmatist  with  a  superficial  varnish  of  criticism.  Kant's 
great  service  consists  to  Herbart  in  the  distinction 
between  appearance  and  thing-in-itself.  All  appearance 
points  to  being,  of  which  it  is  the  ai:)pearance.  Every 
distinction  in  the  phenomenon  corresi3onds  to  a  distinc- 
tion in  the  thing-in-itself.  The  problem  of  philo- 
sophy is  to  pierce  through  the  given  phenomena  to  the 
reality  of  which  it  is  the  sign.  Physics  deals  only  with 
the  phenomenon,  metaphysics,  with  the  entity  which  the 
phenomenon  denotes.  We  are  driven  to  investigate  this, 
inasmuch  as  the  phenomenon  as  given,  is  seen  on  closer 
inspection  to  involve  a  contradiction,  and  hence,  by  the 
laws  of  thought,  we  are  compelled  to  resolve  this  contra- 
diction in  order  to  make  experience  intelligible.  Change, 
for  instance,  is  given  in  the  phenomenal  world  ;  but  change 
is  a  self-contradictory  conception,  as  old  Zeno  had  shown ; 
the  problem  therefore  arises  (since,  according  to  Herbart, 
reality  can  involve  no  contradiction),  to  explain  the  con- 
ditions which  create  for  us  the  appearance  of  change. 
Metaphysics,  therefore  (and  be  it  remembered,  Herbart  is 
speaking  here  of  dogmatic  metaphysics,  that  is,  of  meta- 


304  MODEEN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

physics  in  tbe  pre-Kantian  sense  of  the  word)  is  not  to  be 
rejected  in  the  summary  manner  of  the  Kantians,  but 
rather  to  be  reformed ;  the  reformation  consisting  in  the 
recognition  of  the  fact  that  it  is  the  science  of  the  integra- 
tion of  empirical  conceptions,  by  which  the  reality  at  their 
basis  is  distinguished  from  the  illusory  form  they  assume 
in  ordinary  consciousness. 

Herbart  retains  Wolfs  division  of  the  science  in  the 
main.  He  terms  the  first  portion,  "  General  Metaphysics," 
and  the  second,  "  Applied  Metaphysics."  "  General 
Metaphysics  "  covers  Ontology,  the  special  or  "  Applied 
Metaph} sics,"  "Philosophy  of  Nature,"  (cosmology), 
"  Kational  Psychology  "  and  "  Rational  Theology."  The 
latter,  Herbart,  in  this  respect  exhibiting  his  affiliation  to 
Kant,  can  only  attain  to  from  the  "  practical "  standpoint. 
The  first  part  of  the  "  General  Metaphysics "  is  closely 
connected  with  logic.  Herbart  here  expounds  his  general 
method.  A  contradiction  occurs  when  intelligibility 
and  fact  do  not  coincide  ;  for  instance,  where  two  terms 
are  found  in  combination,  which  can  nevertheless  onlj' 
be  conceived  in  separation.  U'his  is  the  case  with  the 
connection  of  cause  and  eifect  where  the  cause,  inasmuch 
as  it  precedes  the  effect,  cannot  be  considered  as  equivalent 
to  the  latter,  and  on  the  other  hand,  inasmuch  as  it 
implicitly  contains  the  efi'ect  must  be  considered  as 
equivalent  to  it.  This  contradiction  is  resolved  when  the 
first  term,  the  cause,  is  conceived  as  a  plurality,  which, 
taken  individually,  has  no  resemblance  to  the  second  term, 
the  efi'ect,  but  which,  in  its  totality,  produces  the  effect, 
\^h.2it  must  be  conceived,  in  short,  but  cannot  be  conceived 
as  one,  must  be  conceived  as  many.  This  Herbart  calls 
the  method  of  relations,  and  compares  it  to  the  reduction  of 
a  composite  direction  of  motion  to  its  simple  components. 

The  second  part  of  "General  Metaphysics,"  the  Ontology, 
opens  with  a  panegyric  on  Kant  for  having  showTi  in  his 
refutation  of  the  "  ontological  argument,"  that  the  con- 
ception of  being  contains  no  distinct  ichat,  but  only  a  that-, 
in  other  words,  that  it  is  mere  position,  apart  from  all  con- 
tent. Inasmuch  as  the  conception  of  being  as  mere  position 
excludes  all  negation,  so  the  quality  of  being  also  excludes 
all  negation,  in  other  words,  all  distinction  of  degree,  and 


Epoch  II.]  HERBART.  305 

all  change  which  necessarily  implies  negation.  To  have 
seen  this  was  the  great  merit  of  the  Eleatics  and  their 
successors  the  Atomists.  It  is  only  by  the  assumption  of 
a  multitude  of  real  essences,  or  as  Herhart  terms  it,  a 
*'  Qualitative  Atomism  "  that  the  contradiction  involved  in 
the  inherence  of  many  qualities  in  one  substance  can  be 
resolved.  The  conception  of  substance  itself  is  capable  of 
reduction  to  that  of  causality.  It  is  only  thus  that  the 
notion  of  substance  can  be  rendered  intelligible ;  just  as  it 
is  only  by  the  relation  of  cause  and  etfect  that  the  ordinary 
mind  renders  the  fact  of  change  intelligible  to  itself. 
As  we  have  seen  above,  the  conception  of  causality  itself 
requires  a  "  working-out "  (Bearheitung),  but  in  this  process 
of  clarifying  conceptions  by  purging  them  of  the  contra- 
dictions they  contain,  we  must  not  rest  satisfied  with  the 
merely  phenomenal  or  physical,  but  must  continue  the 
process  until  we  arrive  at  the  metaphysical — until  we 
discover  the  processes  of  the  supersensible-real,  itself. 
We  here  find  that  by  reason  of  its  absolute  simplicity, 
though  no  change  can  take  place  in  the  individual  essence, 
yet  that  this  may  very  easily  be  the  case  with  the 
combination  of  two  or  more  such  essences,  in  each  of 
which  a  disturbance,  and  in  consequence  a  resistance,  is 
generated,  as  is  the  case  with  our  own  mind  (the  only 
essence,  whose  inner  processes  can  be  directly  known  to 
us)  when  we  feel  a  contrast  between  colours  or  tones.  Since 
by  these  disturbances  and  resistances  or  "  acts  of  self-pre- 
servation," as  Herbart  terms  them,  all  the  phenomena  of 
physics  and  empirical  psychology  may  be  explained,  they 
may  be  regarded  as  the  groundwork  of  the  "  philosophy 
of  nature,"  and  of  psychology. 

Herbart  gives  the  name  of  Synechology  to  that  portion 
of  his  doctrine  which  refers  to  space  and  time  and  matter. 
According  to  this,  space  is  indeed  appearance,  though  not 
as  Kant  imagined,  a  subjective  merely,  but  rather  an 
objective  appearance,  in  such  wise  that  where  objective 
multitude  is  given  uncombined,  but  so  that  it  may  be 
combined,  it  must  assume  for  every  intelligence  the  form 
of  externality.  This  intelligible  space  of  Herbart's  is  not 
to  be  considered  as  a  continuum  like  the  "  given  "  space  of 
the  phenomenon.     The    latter  involves  a  contradiction, 


306  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

for  the  extended  object  covers  many  different  portions  of 
space  lying  outside  one  another,  and  yet  in  extension 
though  the  one  is  severed  into  many  it  is  still  thought  as 
one.  In  intension  the  same  contradiction  appears  as  in 
extension.  In  conceiving  matter,  we  begin  a  division 
which  we  must  carry  on  to  infinity,  because  every  portion 
has  to  be  conceived  as  extended.  Each  of  the  dimensions 
of  real  or  intelligible  space  is  a  rigid  line  differing 
according  to  the  sum  of  its  tangents.  Herbart  expounds 
this  idea  on  geometrical  piinciples  with  a  fulness  charac- 
teristic of  him  in  matters  mathematicnl,  into  which 
exposition  we  need  not  enter.  As  with  space  so  with 
time;  it  consists  in  a  sum  of  points  of  buccession. 
It  appears  a  continuum  because  at  the  close  of  one 
series  of  changes  another  immediately  begins.  The  con- 
junction of  causality  with  space  and  time,  gives  us  the 
data  for  the  explanation  of  matter,  the  attraction  and 
repulsion  apparently  inherent  in  which  must  not  be 
regarded  as  existent  forces,  but  merely  as  the  appearance 
resulting  from  tbe  primary  combination  of  real  essences — 
a  view  which  obviates  the  absurd  assumption  of  action 
at  a  distance.  Since  space  is  merely  an  accident  of  real 
entity,  it  follows  that  real  esf^ences  are  not  necessarily 
subject  to  space-relations,  and  therefore  that  that  which 
requires  explanation  is  not  so  much  motion,  as  rest,  namely, 
the  particular  case,  from  out  of  an  infinite  possibility  of 
cases,  in  which  velocity  =  0.  Herbart  seeks  to  deduce  the 
phenomena  of  chemistry  and  phj^sics  from  four  cases  of 
the  opposition  of  elements.  These  may  be  either  strong 
and  equal,  strong  and  unequal,  weak  and  equal,  or  weak 
and  unequal. 

The  Eidology  is,  as  it  were,  the  vestibule  of  Psychology, 
as  Synechology  is  of  Cosmolog}'.  The  conception  of  the 
Ego  involves  the  contradiction  of  the  inherence  of  the  many 
in  the  one,  a  circumstance  especially  noticeable  in  this  case, 
inasmuch  asself-consciousne>s  presents  the  Ego  in  percep- 
tion as  a  complete  unity.  Furthermore,  it  is  a  contradiction, 
since  the  knowledge  of  the  knowing  subject  seems  to 
demand  in  its  turn  a  knowledge  of  this  knowledge,  and  so 
on  to  infinity ;  again,  there  is  a  formal  contiadiction  also 
involved  in  the  identit}^  of  the  Ego  as  object  with  the  Ego 


Erocn  II.]  HERBART.  307 

as  subject ;  this  seeming  identity  remains  therefore  to  he 
explained.  The  sonl,  in  common  with  everything  real  (in 
Ilerbart's  sense),  is  an  absolutely  simple  and  indestructible 
entity,  and  hence  cannot  be  the  substratum  of  a  plurality 
of  faculties.  Its  quality  is  like  that  of  every  other  entity, 
unknown,  although,  as  above  observed,  it  is  the  only 
entitj^  of  which  we  can  know  immediately  the  internal 
processes,  namely  tho^o  disturbances  and  resistances  or 
"  acts  of  self-preservation,"  which  give  rise  to  sense- 
presentation.  A  thorough  investigation  of  the  nature  of 
the  soul  necessarily  begins  with  the  primitive  impressions 
of  sound,  colour,  &c.  The  fact  that  these  are  quanti- 
tatively distinct,  and  that  "  acts  of  self-preservation  "  since 
they  are  positive  cannot  destroy,  but  only  limit  one 
another,  shows  that  these  latter  must  be  subject  to  a 
mathematical  regularity,  a  regularity  already  acknow- 
ledged in  one  class  of  these  reciprocal  limitations,  namely, 
the  harmony  of  musical  tones.  Herbart  therefore  claims  a 
mathematical  treatment  for  the  investigation.  The  clue 
to  the  whole  subsequent  exposition  is  contained  in 
the  sentence  "every  limited  perception  persists  in  the 
soul,  as  an  effort  to  perceive."  This  justifies,  in  the 
opinion  of  Herbart,  an  analogy  with  the  laws  of  elastic 
bodies,  and,  other  things  being  equal,  even  the  assumption 
of  the  validity  of  the  same  laws  in  Psychology.  In 
accordance  with  this,  a  "  static  of  the  mind  "  is  furnished 
in  which  the  equilibrium  of  perceptions  is  discussed. 
Herbart  terms  the  sum  of  limitation  the  quantum  of  per- 
ceiving contained  in  two  combined  presentments.  That 
which  is  not  limited,  or  converted  into  effort,  is  termed  the 
"  perceptive  remnant,"  a  mathematical  calculation  demon- 
strating that  no  single  perception,  however  strong,  suffices 
completely  to  displace  another,  to  effect  which  it  requires 
at  least  two  such  perceptions.  The  jDoint  which  constitutes 
the  boundary  between  entity,  as  striving  or  effort,  and  as 
conscious  perception,  is  termed  the  "threshold  of  con- 
sciousness." The  union  of  perceptions  of  different  classes, 
as,  for  instance,  sound  and  meaning  in  the  spoken  word, 
Herbart  terms  comiolication ;  the  union  of  those  of  the 
same  class,  blending.  In  the  "  mechanic  of  the  mind," 
Herbart   considers   the   movement  of    perceptions,   their 

X  2 


308  MODEEN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

sinking  and  rising,  memory,  association,  &c.,  in  the  guise 
of  the  same  mathematical  formulae  as  before. 

In  the  analytical  part  of  his  Psychology  he  endeavours 
to  show  how  all  given  psychological  phenomena  may  be 
explained  by  the  formulee  without  recourse  to  the  hypo- 
thesis of  special  faculties.  It  is  scarcely  necessary  to  say 
that  for  Herbart  the  distinction  between  the  empirical  and 
the  pure  Ego  does  not  exist.  For  him,  the  mind,  the 
psychological  object,  is  the  only  fact  standing  in  need 
of"  explanation.  Herbart,  on  the  ground  of  his  onto- 
logy, notwithstanding,  protests  against  psychology  being 
confounded  with  metaphysic  or  logic.  All  facts  have  a 
psychological  side,  but  this  by  no  means  exhausts  their 
whole  significance.  The  confusion  of  the  empirical  or 
psychological  space,  which  is  a  continuum,  with  the  intelli- 
gible space,  which  is  an  interruptum,  was,  in  Herbart's 
opinion,  one  of  the  greatest  errors  into  which  Kant  fell.  The 
same  applies  to  time  as  to  space.  As  to  the  categories, 
when  correctly  viewed  they  are  seen  to  coincide  with  the 
forms  of  language,  and  a  complete  syst&m  of  them  presup- 
poses a  universal  grammar. 

Esthetics  is  the  science  treating  of  that  which  pleases 
on  account  of  its  beauty  apart  from  any  ulterior  reason. 
It  has  therefore  to  be  distinguished  from  the  desirable 
and  the  pleasant,  both  of  which  have  reference  to  a  sub- 
jective interest;  after  this,  the  problem,  here  as  in  every 
other  department,  is  to  resolve  the  beautiful  as  given, 
into  its  simplest  elements.  Such  an  analysis  will  show 
us  that  these  elements  consist  not  of  entities  but  of 
relations;  the  problem  therefore  becomes,  to  exhibit  the 
simplest  relations  which  can  call  forth  a  disinterested 
sense  of  pleasure.  This  has,  as  yet,  only  been  done 
in  one  of  the  arts,  namely,  Music.  What  the  theory  of 
harmony  and  thorough-bass  does  for  Music,  remains 
a  desideratum  as  regards  the  other  Arts.  Ethics  itself 
may  be  regarded  as  a  branch  of  J^sthetics.  In  Ethics 
we  have  to  exhibit  the  simplest  relations  of  will,  or 
combinations  of  motives  which  produce  the  sense  of 
moral  beauty.  To  ask  why  such  motives  please  and  their 
contraries  displease,  is  as  absurd  as  to  ask  why  one  chord 
is  agreeable  to  the  ear  and  another  not  ?     That  these  re- 


ErocH  IL]  HERBAKT.  309 

lations,  which  may  be  termed  sample-conceptions,  or  Ideas, 
are  unconditionally  valid,  Kant  felt,  and  he  is  much  to  be 
blamed  for  having  mixed  them  up  with  metaphysical 
notions,  such  as  power  and  he'mg,  with  which  they  have 
no  connection.  Hevbart  is  especially  severe  on  Kant's 
*'  Transcendental  Freedom,"  an  assumption  on  which 
neither  punishment  nor  education  can  be  explained,  since 
they  both  presuppose  actions  to  be  the  necessary  results 
of  character.  Duties  may  be  divided  into  such  as  concern 
oneself,  such  as  concein  society,  and  finally  such  as 
concern  the  future  of  both  the  individual  and  society. 

There  are  two  points  in  which  the  theoretical  and 
practical  sides  of  philosophy  meet,  and  the  consideration 
of  which  pre-supposes  a  knowledge  of  both  departments. 
The  combination  of  "  practical  philosophy  "  and  "  philo- 
sophy of  nature,"  furnishes  the  "theory  of  religion;" 
their  combination  with  Psychology  the  "  theory  of 
pedagogic."  The  former  Herbart  did  not  systematically 
work  out,  and  his  utterances  respecting  it  are  conveyed 
in  a  somewhat  detached  form.  Pedagogic,  or  the  theory 
of  Education,  is  his  great  subject  outside  philosophy 
proper.  Its  end  is  of  course  the  moulding  of  the  moral 
character.  Freewill  and  Fatrilist  theories  are  alike  to  be 
rejected.  The  practical  ideas  and  the  psychological 
certainty  of  the  action  and  reaction  of  particular  per- 
ceptions are  a  true  guide  for  the  teacher.  Eegulation  and 
teaching  should  be  combined.  The  object  of  both  is 
training,  i.e.  to  give  strength  to  the  nioral  character  and  to 
enable  the  pupil  in  the  end  to  undertake  his  own  education. 
Herbart  sees  in  Politics  merely  an  extended  Pedagogic. 
Political  forms  are  for  him  of  little  account.  His  sheet- 
anchor  is  the  individual  character. 

Though  it  is  not  to  be  denied  that  there  are  suggestive 
passages  and  some  clever  and  just  criticisms  in  Herbart's 
writings,  jQi  as  a  system  his  philosophy  may  not  unfairly 
be  described  as  a  grotesque  abortion.  Its  mathematical 
dress  has  alone  saved  it  from  oblivion.  An  adept  mathe- 
matician can  always  present  an  idea  in  a  shape  to 
command  the  attention  of  the  learned  world  irrespective 
of  its  intrinsic  value.  The  attraction  a  mathematic 
mode  of  treatment  possesses  for  the  modern  "  cultured ' 


310  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

mind  is  irresistible,  and  operates  quite  independently  of 
any  consideration  as  to  the  susceptibility  of  the  given 
subject-matter  to  such  a  treatment.  To  wrap  a  theory  up 
skilfully  in  mathematical  formula3,  though  in  itself  it  may 
be  the  baldest  nonsense,  is  the  surest  passport  in  the 
jDresent  day  to  acquiring  the  reputation  of  a  "serious 
thinker."  Herbart  is  in  this  happy  position.  Although 
he  commits  all  the  errors  against  which  Kant's  '  Critique ' 
was  directed,  although  he  is  essentially  a  pre-Kantian  in 
his  construction,  yet  the  magical  charm  of  his  mathematics 
has  sufficed  to  give  him  a  place  in  the  history  of  specula- 
tive thought  he  certainly  would  not  otherwise  possess. 
Herbart  left  behind  him  a  school  to  which  the  editor  of 
his  completed  works,  Harten stein  (also  the  editor  of  the 
well-known  edition  of  Kant's  works  bearing  his  name), 
belonged. 


HEGEL. 

Georg  WiLHELii  Feiedeich  Hegel  was  born  at  Stuttgart, 
August  27th,  1770.  His  father  was  an  officer  in  the  tiscal 
service ;  his  mother,  whom  he  lost  in  his  thirteenth  year, 
seems  to  have  been  a  woman  of  some  little  education,  and 
of  more  than  ordinary  intelligence.  He  studied  'at  the 
University  of  Tubingen,  both  in  the  philosophical  and 
theological  faculties.  As  a  student  he  was  the  author  of 
one  or  two  essays  on  philosophical  subjects,  and  he  also 
publicly  defended  two  dissertations.  His  private  reading 
during  this  period,  of  the  works  of  Kant,  Jacobi,  and 
other  philosophers,  in  addition  to  those  of  Herder,  Lessing 
and  Schiller,  seems  to  have  powerfully  influenced  him. 
Besides  this,  he  carried  on  at  the  same  time  A^dth  much 
enthusiasm  his  studies  in  Greek  literature  and  history. 

Like  Fichte  and  Herbart,  on  leaving  the  university 
he  took  a  position  as  private  tutor,  and  to  make  the 
parallel  more  complete,  in  Switzerland  (at  Berne).  U'his 
did  not  hinder  his  own  studies,  which  he  zealously  followed 
up,  engaging  at  the  same  time  in  a  correspondence  with 


ErocH  n.]  HEGEL.  311 

Schelling  who  was  still  studying  at  Tiibingen.  Curiously 
enough,  his  first  important  work  Avas  a  "  Life  of  Jesus," 
which  was  based  on  the  distinction  already  insisted  upon 
by  Lessing,  between  the  doctrines  of  the  founder  of  Chris- 
tianity and  the  dogmas  of  the  Church.  The  influence  of  the 
Auf Mar  ling  was,  however,  strong  in  Hegel  at  this  time,  the 
special  form  it  took  being  that  of  Hellenism.  In  1797  he 
entered  upon  a  similar  position  to  that  whioh  he  had  held 
at  Berne,  at  Frankfort-on- the -Maine ;  but  Hegel  was  irre- 
sistibly drawn  to  Jena,  the  philosophical  metropolis, 
whither  he  repaired  in  Januarj^  1801.  It  was  here  that 
his  thoughts  began  to  assume  a  systematic  form,  though 
he  deemed  himself  at  this  time,  in  the  main,  a  follower  of 
his  younger  contemporary  Schelling,  with  whom  he  subse- 
quently worked  in  common,  for  the  spread  of  the  "  System 
of  Identity,"  on  the  Krittsche  Journal  der  Philosophies  to 
which  he  contributed  most  of  the  articles. 

The  difterences  between  the  two  thinkers  soon  became 
apparent  on  the  departure  of  Schelling  from  Jena,  and 
with  the  production  of  Hegel's  first  great  work,  *  The 
Phenomenology  of  the  Mind '  (Phanomenologie  des  Geistes)^ 
in  1806,  the  wide  divergence  in  their  intellectual  capacities 
became  obvious.  In  consequence  of  the  Napoleonic  war 
then  raging,  Hegel  left  Jena  soon  after  this,  and  became 
editor  of  the  Bamberger  Zeitung^  a  post  he  subsequently 
threw  up  for  the  directorship  of  a  public  school  at  Niirn- 
berg.  He  remained  here  until  the  year  1816,  and  here, 
among  other  works,  his  great  "  Logic  "  was  written.  In 
the  autumn  of  1816  Hegel  entered  the  chair  of  j^hilosophy 
at  Heidelberg,  just  vacated  by  Fries.  During  his  stay  at 
Heidelberg  he  wrote  his  '  Encyclopedia  of  the  Philoso- 
phical Sciences.'  Finally,  on  October  22nd,  1818,  Hegel 
became  professor  in  Berlin.  During  the  Berlin  period,  the 
only  large  work  completed  by  him  was  '  The  Elements 
of  the  Philosophy  of  Right '  (^Grundlinien  der  Fhilosophie 
des  Mechts).  His  disciples,  however,  after  his  death, 
pxiblished  the  lectures  delivered  during  this  time  on  the 
Philosophy  of  History,  Art,  and  Religion,  as  well  as  on 
the  History  of  Philosophy.  Hegel  died  at  Berlin,  of 
cholera,  on  the  14th  of  November,  1831. 

The  life  of  Hegel  was  written  by  his  disciple  Rosen- 


312  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

kranz.       His    complete    works  (including     the   lectures) 
occupy  eighteen  volumes. 

The  Hegelian  System. 

We  now  take  up  again  the  direct  line  of  thought 
represented  by  Kant,  Fichte,  and  Schelling,  a  line  which 
culminates  in  the  great  thinker  whose  name  heads  this 
section.  The  system  of  Hegel  may  be  best  described  as 
Panlogism.  The  Real  or  Concrete  is  nothing  but  a  s;yTithesis 
of  relations,  each  of  which,  taken  by  itself,  and  apart  from 
the  whole  into  which  it  enters,  is  abstract,  and  therefore 
unreal.  The  ultimate  principle  of  all  knowledge  is  of 
course  the  pure  form  of  the  unity  of  the  consciousness,  the 
•'  Synthetic  Unity  of  Apperception  "  of  Kant,  the  "  Pure 
Ego"  of  Fichte.  This  is  the  "Concept"  (Begriff)  oi 
Hegel.  But  the  synthesis  so  stated,  that  is,  by  itself,  is 
formal ;  it  is  a  unity  of  thought,  of  consciousness  as  such, 
and  of  nothing  else  but  thought  or  consciousness.  But 
thought  or  consciousness  is  in  its  nature  relative.  Think- 
ing or  knowing  implies  a  striking-out  of  relations,  a  fixing 
of  contrasts,  a  limitation  of  a  conscious  state,  which  is  in 
its  turn  nothing  but  the  limitation  of  another  conscious 
state,  and  so  on  to  infinity.  But  the  infinity  is  not  that  of 
an  infinitely  produced  straight  line  (to  employ  an  analogy), 
but  rather  that  of  the  circle  ;  or,  better  still,  of  the  spiral. 
The  Concrete  or  the  Eeal  which  is  Experience-in-general, 
is  the  system  of  all  possible  momenta  or  determinations 
of  knowledge,  thought,  or  consciousness.  This  system, 
which  embraces  all  possible  oppositions  and  antagonisms, 
considered  as  a  whole,  is  the  Logos  or  Idee  in  its  reality,  the 
*'  Concrete  Idea,"  as  Hegel  terms  it.  Considered  abstractly, 
the  "  Idea  "  is  the  formal  unity  spoken  of  above,  which 
embraces  all  differences,  which  maintains  itself  in  all  these 
differences,  and  which  is  their  final  principle  of  explanation. 
"VVe  need  hardly  repeat  what  we  have  already  said  when 
treating  of  Fichte,  namely,  that  this  unity,  inasmuch  as 
the  determinations  of  thought  all  and  severally  presuppose 
it,  can  never  become  itself  an  object,  or,  which  is  the  same 
thing,  a  determination  of  thought — that  is  to  say,  it  can 
never  enter  the  sphere  of  the  empirical  consciousness. 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  313 

Empiricism  and  Scepticism  in  j)hilosopliy,  in  undermining 
the  distinctions  of  the  ordinary  consciousness,  and  of  the 
philosophy  which  takes  its  immediate  stand  upon  it,  paves 
tlie  "svay  for  the  true  synthetic  view.  Thus  Scepticism 
shows  that  on  the  ordinary  crude  dualistic  assumption  of 
the  absolute  independence  of  subject  and  object,  mind  and 
matter,  perceiver  and  perceived,  knowledge  would  be  im- 
possible. It  forces  us  therefore  to  reconsider  the  prelimi- 
nary assumption  which  we  have  hitherto  received  as  an 
unquestionable  truth.  The  same  with  every  fixed  dis- 
tinction, great  and  small,  im^^ortant  and  unimportant;, 
every  such  distinction  will  be  found  on  examination,  when 
consistently  carried  out,  to  refute  itself — that  is,  to  contain 
the  germ  of  its  own  destruction  or  negation,  or,  as  Hegel 
has  it,  its  own  "  internal  dialectic." 

In  the  word  Dialectic  we  have  the  key  to  the  whole 
Hegelian  system.  The  method  of  Hegel  is  the  dialectical 
method,  and  to  have  discovered  the  full  significance  of  this 
method,  to  have  struck  upon  the  innermost  dynamic  prin-, 
ciple  of  the  world,  gives  to  Hegel  a  pre-eminence  in  a  sense 
above  all  other  thinkers.  Herakleitos  of  Ephesus  caught 
a  glimpse  of  the  principle  when  he  said,  "  all  things  flow," 
and  "  there  is  nothing  that  comes  into  being  but  it  forthwith 
ceases  to  be."  Zeno  of  Elea  also  caught  sight  of  it  when 
he  sought  to  convince  the  ordinary  man,  who  could  not 
conceive  of  a  world  based  on  contradiction,  of  the  truth  of 
Parmenides'  doctrines,  by  placing  him  in  the  dilemma  of 
either  admitting  the  sense-world  to  be  contradictory,  or 
denying  its  existence  altogether,  not  doubting  but  that  he 
would  accept  the  latter  alternative.  The  Sophists  and 
Sokrates  saw  in  it  respectively,  the  former  the  destruction 
of  all  certitude,  and  the  latter,  a  new  means  for  the  attain- 
ment of  truth  from  the  very  fact  of  its  potency  in  under- 
mining the  would-be  certitudes  of  current  opinion.  In 
Plato,  the  principle  obtained  its  fullest  recognition  in  the 
ancient  world.  Plato's  philosophy  is  essentially  an  exhi- 
bition of  the  dialectic  immanent  in  all  knowledge.  Aris- 
totle, although  the  general  bearing  of  his  mind  might  be 
supposed  to  tend  in  a  different  direction,  nevertheless 
places  it  in  the  fore-front  of  his  system  in  his  distinction 
of  matter  and  form,  and  his  recognition  of  all  reality  as  the 


314  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY,  [Epoch  II. 

s^-nthesis  of  matter  and  form.  In  all  periods,  when  the 
tWo  great  thinkers  of  antiquity  have  held  a  foremost  place 
in  the  higher  thought  of  the  world — periods,  for  instance, 
Kuch  as  that  of  the  decline  of  ancient  philosophy  and  of 
scholasticism — it  has  never  been  left  quite  out  of  view 
however  much  obscured ;  but  from  Descartes  and  Bacon 
to  Kant  it  had  practically  lapsed  into  oblivion.  In  Kant's 
"  Transcendental  Analytic  "  and  "  Transcendental  Dialectic,'* 
it  again  appears,  though  overlaid  with  much  extraneous 
material.  In  Fichte  it  receives  a  fairly  definite  expres- 
sion ;  but  it  was  reserved  for  Hegel  to  recognise  its  full 
bearing  as  the  principle  of  knowledge,  and  the  method  of 
philosophic  investigation.  Among  poets,  Goethe  has 
best  caught  the  beat  of  the  world-rhythm  when  he  makes 
the  Erdgeist  in  Faust  exclaim 

*'  In  Beiug's  floods,  in  Action's  stoi-m 
I  walk  and  work,  above  beneath, 
Work  and  weave  in  endless  motion! 
Birth  and  Death 
An  infinite  ocean, 
A  seizing  and  giving 
The  tire  of  Living: 
'Tis  thus  at  the  roaring  Loom  of  Time  I  ply. 
And  weave  for  God  the  Garment  thou  seest  Him  by." 

Hegel  claims  for  his  system  that  all  antitheses,  all  oppo- 
sing principles,  that  have  ever  held  sway  in  philosophy, 
are  therein  at  once  recognised  and  transcended,  that  is, 
shown  to  be  necessary,  but  incomplete,  taken  by  them- 
selves. The  first, condition  of  philosophising,  as  observed 
in  connection  with  Plato,  is  to  lift  ourselves  above  the 
immediate — the  liere,  the  this,  and  the  noio  of  things.  All 
intellectual  life  is  more  or  less  an  effort  to  break  away 
from  immediate  appearances  and  immediate  interests. 
Kant  has  said  with  truth  that  the  Ptolemaic  system  of 
Astronomy  is  the  one  naturally  most  intelligible  to  us,  not 
because  it  is  simpler  than  the  Copernican  system,  but 
because,  in  spite  of  confusedness  and  clumsiness,  it  accounts 
for  astronomical  phenomena  on  the  hypothesis  of  all 
things  revolving  round  ourselves,  viz.  our  Earth.  The 
superior  simplicity  and  order  of  the  Copernican  system  did, 
notwithstanding,  in  the  long  run  win   the  victory  over 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  315 

common -sense  consecrated  by  tradition.  The  anthropo- 
morphism and  myth  of  primitive  man  is  an  expression 
of  the  difficulty  man  experiences  in  divesting  his  view  of 
things  of  the  influence  of  his  immediate  surroundings  as  he 
conceives  them  to  alfect  his  interests. 

There  is  nothing  which  presupposes  such  a  revohition 
in  our  mental  life  as  tlie  ability  to  view  the  world  from 
the  synthetic  or  sjieculative  point  of  view — as  a  dialectical 
movement.  All  accustomed  habits  of  thought,  all  the  fixed 
distinctions  in  which  the  intellectual  wealth  of  the  average 
man  consists,  have  to  be  ruthlessly  cast  into  the  caldron 
of  an  all-consuming  Logic.  Their  hard  outlines  then 
begin  to  alter  shape,  and  finally  to  lose  shape  entirely,  as 
they  become  mixed  in  a  seething  mass  where  one  distinc- 
tion blends  into  its  023posite,  the  whole  acquiring  for  a 
moment  a  new  shape  only  in  its  turn  to  give  place  to 
another,  and  yet  another.  "  So  strong,"  says  Hegel,  speak- 
ing of  the  exposition  of  his  system,  "  is  the  sense  of  the 
opposition  of  true  and  false,  that  it  has  accustomed  men 
to  expect  either  agreement  with,  or  contradiction  of,  some 
existing  philosojihical  system,  and,  in  explaining  such, 
only  to  see  this  or  that."  If  we  clarify  our  conceptions  of 
truth  and  falsehood — that  is,  subject  them  to  the  purifying 
fire  of  dialectic — we  shall  see  that  they  change  their  con- 
tent with  our  jDoint  of  view,  that  their  content  is  not  fixed, 
but  fluid.  "  The  bud  vanishes  with  the  appearance  of  the 
blossom,  and  one  may  say  that  the  one  is  contradicted 
by  the  other;  the  fruit  again  proclaims  the  blossom  a 
spurious  form  of  the  plant's  existence,  the  truth  of  the 
one  passes  over  to  the  other.  These  forms  are  not  merely 
distinct,  but  crush  each  other  out  as  being  mutually 
incompatible.  But  their  fluid  nature  constitutes  them 
none  the  less  momenta  of  that  organic  unity  wherein  they 
not  alone  cease  to  conflict,  but  to  which  one  is  as  necessary 
as  the  other,  which  equal  necessity  makes  the  life  of  the 
whole." 

The  Hegelian  dialectic  is  based  on  the  recognition  of 
identity  in  difference,  of  the  fact  that  all  affirmation 
implies  negation,  all  negation  afiirmation.  In  all  things 
there  is  a  capacity  unrealised,  and  a  capacity  realised; 
the  first  is  the  material  moment,  the  second  the  formal 


316  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

moment.  The  acorn  is  the  unrealised  capacity  of  the  oak, 
it  is  realised  as  oak.  The  realisation  of  the  capacity  of  a 
thing  is  the  negation  of  that  thing  as  actually  existent. 
The  possibility  or  capacity  present  in  the  child  is  realised 
in  the  man,  but  manhood  is  the  negation  of  childhood — 
child  qua  child  vanishes  in  the  man,  he  exists  no  longer, 
any  more  than  though  he  were  dead.  Every  step  in  the 
growth  or  progress  of  the  child  is  a  step  towards  the 
negation  of  childhood.  Again,  animal  life  exists  only  by 
virtue  of  the  continuous  destruction  or  decomposition  of 
the  tissues  of  which  it  is  actually  comjDOsed.  Arrest  this 
process  of  destruction  or  negation,  and  the  animal  dies. 
The  fatal  effect  of  many  of  the  mineral  poisons  is  simply 
due  to  their  action  in  stopping  the  natural  process  of  the 
destruction  of  the  organic  tissues,  a  jDrocess  which  is 
essential  to  animal  life.  Animal  life  presupposes  organic 
life  ;  but  the  latter  is,  as  Hegel  would  term  it,  the  negative 
moment  of  the  former — it  is  the  means  only,  and 
not  the  end.  The  animal  life  can  only  realise  or  main- 
tain itself  in  and  through  the  negation  of  the  nega- 
tive moment;  in  other  words,  the  continuous  destruc- 
tion of  the  organic  matte?-  (the  tissue)  is  essential  to  the 
reality  of  the  animal  form  (the  living  body).  This 
dialectic  runs  through  all  things ;  it  is  the  ultimate  ex- 
pression of  all  reality,  and  it  may  be  discovered  by 
analysis  on  every  plane  of  reality.  Its  recognition  cannot 
fail  to  give  us  a  completely  new  view  of  the  world-order. 
Uur  ultimate  aim  in  every  science  will  be  henceforward 
to  discover  the  course  of  its  dialectic,  or  rather  the 
dialectic  of  its  subject-matter,  since  this  is  the  key  to  its 
mysteries.  The  significance  of  formal  logic  with  its  laws 
of  thought  will  be  seen  to  disappear  Avhen  experience  is 
viewed  from  this  more  comprehensive  standpoint.  So  far 
from  its  being  the  case,  as  the  law  of  contradiction  asserts, 
that  a  thing  cannot  both  be  and  not  be,  we  now  know 
that,  in  a  sense,  everything  is,  and  at  the  same  time  is  not, 
in  so  far  as  it  expresses  a  determinate  reality  at  all — omnis 
determinatio  est  negatio.  Since  reality,  i.e.  the  synthesis  of 
experience,  consists  alone  in  the  union  of  contradictories, 
it  necessarily  follows  that  for  experience,  for  consciousness, 
pui'e  affirmation  is  precisely  on  a  level  with  pure  negation 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  317 

since  tliey  are  alike  unreal  and  meaningless.  This  is  all 
Heg-el  intends  by  the,  at  lirst  sight,  astounding  proposition 
with  which  his  Logic  opens,  that  "  being  and  non-being 
are  the  same." 

In  his  first  great  work,  the  '  Phenomenology  of  the 
Mind,'  Hegel  traces  the  natural  development  of  the 
human  mind  from  the  naive  consciousness  of  the  ordinary 
man   to   the   synthetic  standpoint   of   philosophy.      The 

*  Phenomenology '   is   in    fact    a    kind   of    philosophical 

*  Pilgrim's  Progress.'  "  Inasmuch,"  says  Hegel,,  "  as  this 
exposition  only  has  phenomenal  knowledge  for  its  subject, 
it  does  not  exhibit  the  free  movement  of  knowledge  in  its 
scientific  form,  and  must  rather  be  regarded  from  the 
present  standpoint  as  the  course  the  natural  consciousness 
takes  in  its  progress  towards  true  knowledge,  as  the 
pathway  of  the  soul,  passing  through  the  series  of  forms 
which  its  nature  prescribes  as  so  many  stages  of  self- 
purification,  until  it  attains  through  a  complete  expe- 
rience of  itself,  to  a  knowledge  of  that  which  it  is  in 
itself"  {Phanomenologie^  Mnleitung,  p.  61). 

The  immediate  form  of  our  knowledge  is  the  object  as 
being  or  existent  thing.  In  this  we  occupy  a  passive  atti- 
tude, the  attitude  of  naive  sense-perception.  In  this  first 
attitude  of  consciousness  reality  seems  to  be  known  in  its 
simplest  and  purest  form.  All  that  knowledge  here  tells 
us  is  of  the  bare  existence  of  the  thing.  The  object  is 
presented,  as  this  thing  Jiere  and  now.  The  word  this 
itself  simply  means  existence  here  and  now.  But  what  is 
now  ?  "  Let  us  say,  for  instance,  noio  it  is  night.  To  our 
immediate  consciousness  this  is  a  truth.  We  note  it  down 
as  a  truth.  At  noonday  we  look  upon  this  ci-devant 
truth,  and  lo,  it  is  a  meaningless  and  palpable  absurdity  !  " 
The  noio,  notwithstanding,  remains,  but  with  a  totally 
changed  content.  It  proves  itself  to  be  what  Hegel 
terms  a  "  universal  negative."  The  same  remarks  apply  to 
the  other  form  of  the  this^  namely,  the  here.  "  Here  is,  for 
instance,  a  tree.  I  turn  myself  round,  and  this  truth  has 
vanished — has ,  transformed  itself  into  its  opposite.  Here 
is  not  a  tree,  but  rather  a  house.  The  here  does  not 
vanish,  but  it  is  that  which  remains  in  the  disappearance 
of  the  house,  the  tree,  and  so  forth,  and  is  indifferently 


318;  MODERN  FHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

house  or  tree"  {PTianomenologie,  p.  74).  "Pure  being" 
is  of  the  essence  of  this  perceptive  consciousness;  for 
pure  being  is  its  immediateness  as  abstract  form.  A  com- 
parison between  the  relation  of  knowledge  to  its  object, 
as  it  immediately  presents  itself,  with  the  same  relation 
after  it  has  been  acted  upon  by  reflection,  shows  a  consi- 
derable difference.  The  universal  element,  which  seemed 
to  belong  to  the  being  of  the  object,  is  now^  seen  to  lie  in 
our  knowledge  of  the  object.  The  perceptive  certainty 
is  seen  to  subsist  not  in  the  object,  but  in  us.  The  now 
and  here  is  preserved  in  the  Ego.  "  What  does  not 
vanish  is  the  I,  as  universal,  whose  seeing  is  neither  a 
seeing  of  the  tree  nor  the  house,  but  a  simple  seeing,  which 
is  brought  about  b}^  the  negation  of  this  house,  and  so 
forth,  which  is  absolutely  indifferent  to  anything  outside 
itself,  alike  to  the  house  and  the  tree."  Thus  Hegel  begins 
his  '  Phenomenology,'  by  showing  the  contradiction  of 
the  empirical  consciousness  with  its  own  prepossessions, 
to  lead  up  through  the  discussion  of  the  scientific  con- 
sciousness, the  Understanding — in  which  the  abstract 
procedure  im^^licit  in  "common  sense,"  or  the  ordinary 
consciousness,  becomes  explicitly  formulated — to  the  philo- 
sophical consciousness,  the  Eeason,  which  sees  the  true 
significance  of  these  various  standpoints  as  parts  of  an 
organic  whole,  as  related  elements  of  a  synthesis.  This 
is  the  ladder  which,  according  to  Hegel,  the  ordinary  con- 
sciousness has  a  right  to  demand,  to  lead  it  to  the  absolute 
knowledge  of  itself.  The  task  of  the  '  Phenomenology  ' 
is  thus  to  show  the  progress  of  knowledge  from  its  lowest 
to  its  highest  stage  ;  each  stage  is  in  its  turn  shown  to 
involve  a  contradiction,  which  necessitates  progress  to  a 
a  higher  stage.  At  each  of  these  stages  the  immediate 
certitude  or  truth  of  the  stage  is  proved  to  be  illusory,  to 
involve  a  self-deception.  This  is  corrected  in  the  following 
stage,  the  certitude  is  changed,  in  its  turn  to  be  subjected 
to  the  same  process,  until  all  these  stages  are  seen  to  be 
inadequate  in  themselves,  and  to  possess  meaning  and 
significance  only  when  regarded  as  the  necessary  momenta, 
not  of  this  or  that  particular  limited  "or  individual 
consciousness,  but  of  consciousness  conceived  as  one  abso- 
lute all-emb]  acing  totality — Absolute  Geist. 


ErocH  II.]  HEGEL.  319 

Hegel's  dialectic,  we  must  again  repeat,  is  simply  the 
perfecting,  as  regards  its  form  of  Fielite's  dialectic.  Fichto 
had  shown  that  the  in-itselfness  of  the  one  plane  of  con- 
sciousness, was  the  for-itselfness  of  the  next  plane.  Hegel, 
however,  brings  out  into  clear  relief  a  point  on  which 
Fichte  was  somewhat  dubious  (but  Avhich  Plato  and 
Aristotle  had  recognised),  to  wit,  that  the  negation  of  the 
opposite  is  not  absolute,  but  is  rather  double-sided — that  is, 
that  the  opposite  or  preceding  moment  is  no  less  preserved 
than  abolished  in  the  succeeding  moment.  Hegel's  aim  is 
to  show  that  the  mind  is  logically  compelled,  on  pain  of 
its  own  reductio  ad  ahsurdum,  to  force  its  way  on  and  on 
until  it  arrives  at  the  standpoint  of  absolute  knowledge. 
The  six  stages  which  the  mind  has  to  pass  through  in  its 
progress  to  absolute  knowledge  are  from  consciousness  to 
self-consciousness,  thence  to  the  scientific  understanding 
"  the  law  making  and  law-finding  reason,"  in  the  words  of 
Hegel,  thence  to  the  moral  consciousness  (Geist),  thence  to 
the  aasthetic  and  religious  consciousness,  and  thence  to  the 
consciousness  of  knowledge  as  absolute.  But  the  world- 
mind,  as  exhibited  on  the  plane  of  History,  is,  equally  with 
the  individual  mind,  under  the  necessity,  by  virtue  of  its 
constitution,  of  passing  through  the  same  stages.  The 
'  Phenomenology '  shows  therefore  the  stages  that  humanity 
has  had  to  pass  through,  and  which  the  individual  must  also 
pass  through,  before  it  can  attain  to  absclute  knowledge. 
Knowledge  or  science  in  the  Hegelian  sense  consists  in  the 
re-reading  of  experience,  in  the  com^reliending  of  experience 
in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  word. 

Before  we  leave  the  '  Phenomenology,'  the  reader  may 
not  take  it  amiss  if  we  give  a  few  extracts  illustrative  of 
the  style  of  this,  in  some  respects,  greatest  work  of  Hegel. 
Such  extracts,  of  course,  can  give  but  a  v^ry  imperfect 
idea  of  the  whole  to  which  they  belong,  as  may  be 
readily  imagined  from  the  nature  of  Hegel's  thought. 
The  impossibility,  moreover,  of  rendering  many  passages 
adequately  in  another  language,  is  generally  admitted. 
In  the  preface  (Phdnomenologie,  p.  15)  Hegel  observes, 
"  The  truth  is  the  whole.  But  the  whole  is  the  essence 
which  completes  itself  in  its  develojDuient.  It  may  be 
said  of  the  Absolute  that  it  is  essentially  result,  that  not 


320  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

before  the  end  is  it  that  which  it  is  iu  truth :  and  herein 
consists  its  nature,  that  of  being  Eeality,  Subject,  or  Self- 
becoming.  However  absurd  it  may  appear  to  regard  the 
Absolute  as  in  essence,  result,  a  very  little  consideration 
will  correct  this  appearance  of  absurdity.  The  beginning, 
the  principle  or  the  Absolute,  as  it  is  primarily  and  im- 
mediately spoken  of,  is  only  the  universal.  Just  as  little 
as  when  I  say  all  animals^  these  words  can  stand  in  the 
place  of  a  Zoology,  can  the  words  Divine,  Absolute, 
Eternal,  &c.,  express  that  which  is  not  contained  in  them. 
It  is  true  that  only  such  words  can  express  the  intuition 
in  its  immediate  form ;  but  this  is  not  all ;  a  word  which 
is  only  a  passage  to  a  proposition  contains  within  it  an 
otherness  of  becoming  which  has  to  be  retraced ;  it  is  a 
mediation  (  Vermittlung).^' 

The  Absolute,  although  it  contains  within  it  the  syn- 
thesis of  all  contradictions,  considered  as  Absolute,  of  course 
transcends  its  own  immanent  contradictions.  Absolute 
knowledge  is  the  resting-point  in  which  all  contradictions 
are  at  once  preserved  and  abolished,  aufgelioben*^  in  the 
language  of  Hegel.  The  word  mediation  ( Vermittlung)  is 
used  by  Hegel  to  denote  the  negative  moment  of  the 
Dialectical  process,  in  its  purity.  This  leads  us  to  revert 
to  the  question  of  the  concepts  true  and  false.  Hegel 
explains  the  distinction  between  them,  as  viewed  from  the 
standpoint  of  ordinary  consciousness,  and  from  that  of  the 
philosophical  reason.  After  defining  the  false  as  the 
otherness,  the  negativity  of  the  substance  of  the  true,  as 
an  essential  moment  in  the  realisation  of  the  true,  and  yet 
as  not  constituting  an  element  of  the  true  as  such,  he 
proceeds :  "  For  the  sake  of  clearness  in  indicating  the 
moment  of  complete  otherness  its  terminology  must  no 
longer  be  used  where  the  otherness  is  abolished  (aufgehohen). 
Thus  the  expression,  the  unity  of  subject  and  object,  of 
finite  and  infinite,  of  being  and  thought,  &c.,  has  the  in- 
convenience that  these  terms  themselves  connote  what 
they  are  outside  their  unity,  and  therefore  that  in  their 

*  Hegel's  word  aufheben,  which  means  both  "to  preserve  "  and  "  to 
destroy,"  is  a  survival  of  the  unity  of  opposites  upon  which  all  primitive 
languiige  is  based.  (See  Dr.  Carl  Aijel's  essay,  Ueber  den  Gegensinn 
der  Urwurte. — Leipzig,  1884.) 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  321 

unity  they  do  not  mean  what  the  phrase  implies ;  the 
false,  as  false,  is  no  longer  a  moment  of  truth.  Dogmatism 
as  a  mode  of  thought  in  Science,  and  in  the  study  of 
Philosophy,  is  nothing  but  the  opinion  that  the  true 
consists  in  a  proposition  which  is  a  fixed  result,  or  in 
that  which  is  immediately  known.  To  such  questions,  as 
when  Caesar  was  born,  or  how  many  toises  made  a  stadium,  a 
concise  answer  can  be  given.  Similarly  it  is  definitely  true 
that  the  square  of  the  hypothenuse  equals  the  sum  of  the 
squares  of  both  remaining  sides  of  the  right-angled  triangle. 
But  the  nature  of  such  so-called  truth  is  difi"erent  from 
the  nature  of  philosophical  truth  "  (Phdnomenologie,  pp. 
30-1).  A  few  pages  farther  on,  after  the  subject  of  Mathe- 
matical truth  has  been  dealt  with,  and  its  imperfections 
shown,  we  have  the  following  pregnant  sentences  :  "  The 
phenomenon  is  the  coming  and  going,  which  yet  does  not 
come  and  go,  but  is  in  itself,  and  whiqh  constitutes  the 
reality  and  movement  of  the  life  of  truth.  The  true  is  a 
Bacchantian  revel,  in  which  there  is  no  member  that  is 
not  drunken ;  but  yet  because  each,  in  so  far  as  it  severs 
itself  from  the  whole,  is  at  once  dissolved,  this  revel  is  none 
the  less  transparent  and  simple  repose.  In  judging  the 
movement,  though  individual  forms  of  the  mind  do  not 
obtain  as  determinate  thoughts,  they  are,  notwithstanding, 
just  as  much  positive  and  necessary  as  they  are  negative 
and  evanescent  momenta.  In  the  totality  of  the  movement 
— in  the  movement  conceived  as  rest — that  in  it  which 
distinguishes  itself  and  acquires  a  specific  reality,  as  such, 
which  recollects,  preserves  itself,  whose  reality  is  know- 
ledge of  itself,  is  the  immediate  reality  "  (Phdnomenologie, 
j)p.  35-6).  "  In  the  nature  of  that  which  is,"  says  Hegel, 
*'  to  realise  its  conception  in  its  being,  consists  logical 
necessity  generally.  This  alone  is  the  rational,  and  the 
rhythm  of  the  organic  whole ;  it  is  just  as  much  knowledge 
of  the  content,  as  the  content  itself  is  concept  and  essence 
— in  other  words,  it  alone  is  sppculative.  The  concrete  fact, 
as  self-realising,  constitutes  itself  simple  determinateness  ; 
it  thus  raises  itself  to  logical  form,  and  is  in  its  nature  as 
essence.  In  this  movement  consists  its  concrete  reality 
which  is  at  the  same  time  logical  reality.  It  is  therefore 
unnecessary  to  affix  to  the  concrete  content  a  formalism 


322  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IL 

external  thereto  ;  the  former  is  itself  the  transition  to  the 
latter,  which  latter  ceases,  however,  to  be  external  and 
formal,  since  the  form  has  become  native  to  the  process  of 
the  concrete  content  itself"  {Phdnomenologie,  p.  43).  One 
more  quotation  before  we  leave  the '  Phenomenology.'  "  Ex- 
perience," Hegel  observes,  "  is  simply  this,  that  the  content, 
that  is,  consciousness  in  itself,  is  substance,  and  therefore 
object  of  consciousness.  But  this  substance,  which  is 
consciousness,  is  the  process  of  its  becoming  what  it  is  in 
itself;  and  it  is  only  as  this  Becoming,  reflected  into 
itself,  that  it  is,  in  truth,  consciousness.  In  itself  it  is 
the  movement  which  constitutes  knowledge — the  trans- 
formation of  this  in-itselfness  into  for-itselfness,  the  substance 
into  the  subject,  the  object  of  consciousness,  into  the  object 
of  self-consciousness — that  is,  into  the  object  as  in  its  turn 
abolished,  or  in  other  words  into  the  concept.  It  is  a  circle 
returning  in  upon  itself  which  presupposes  its  beginning, 
and  yet  only  attains  it  as  end.  Thus,  in  so  far  as  conscious- 
ness consists  necessarily  in  this  distinction  within  itself, 
itself  as  the  perceived  whole,  confronts  its  simple  self-con- 
sciousness, and  inasmuch  as  it  distinguishes  the  latter,  it 
is  distinguished  in  its  pure  perceived  concept — that  is,  in 
time,  and  in  its  content,  or  in-itselfness.  Substance  has,  as 
subject,  the  primary  inner  necessity  to  display  itself,  as 
what  it  is  in  itself — as  consciousness.  The  complete 
objective  preseij.tation  is  primarily  its  reflection,  or  its 
realisation  as  self"  (PJidnomenologie,  p.  585). 

We  now  turn  to  the  Logic  of  Hegel.  In  the  Logic  we 
have  the  essential  articulations,  or  momenta  of  conscious- 
ness presented,  not  in  the  order  in  which  they  disclose 
themselves  to  the  reflective  understanding,  as  in  the 
*  Phenomenology,'  but  in  the  necessary  or  Logical  order  of 
their  deduction.  The  secret  of  Hegel's  method,  it  will  be 
by  this  time  suflicientl}'  clear  to  the  reader,  lies  in  the  triple 
articulation  of  each  stage  or  plane  of  reality.  Matter  or 
in-itselfness  becomes  negated  as  form  or  for-itselfness.  This 
negation  is  in  its  turn  negated ;  but  the  negation  is  not  ab- 
solute in  either  case,  the  one  form  is  preserved  or,  so  to  speak, 
held  in  solution  in  the  succeeding  one,  notwithstanding  its 
negative  character  considered  j:»er  se.  Thus,  in  the  third 
term,  which  is  the  negation  of  the  negative  of  the  first,  we 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  323 

have  the  completed  moment  as  such.  Tlegel  takes  care  to 
observe,  what  indeed  is  sufficient!}'  obvious,  namely,  that 
his  Logic  might  equally  well  have  been  termed  Meta- 
physic  or  Ontology,  since,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
speculative  thought,  this  distinction  of  departments  can 
no  longer  be  maintained/  The  world,  reality,  experience, 
consists  merely  in  these  logical  determinations  ;  the  sum 
total  of  these  determinations  is  the  Absolute.  Thus  instead 
of  being  able  to  adequately  define  the  Absolute  by  a  single 
phrase,  as  Schelling  thought  he  could,  Hegel  finds  it  im- 
possible to  do  this,  save  in  the  complete  exposition  of  a 
science.  Logic  in  Hegel's  sense  is  this  science  ;  it  is  the 
science  of  the  at  once  all-embracing,  all-determining  Logos 
Idea,  or  Concept,  i.e.  of  consciousness  as  absolute. 

The  categories  of  which  the  Hegelian  Logic  treats,  of 
course  entirely  traverse  the  empirical  distinctions  of  mind 
and  matter,  subject  and  object,  &c.,  since  they  are  pre-sup- 
posed  in  these  distinctions.  Hegel  somewhere  calls  them 
"  the  souls  of  all  reality."  But  taken  by  themselves,  as 
spread  out  before  the  reflective  understanding,  they  are  pure 
abstractions,  and  the  Logic  is  thus  none  the  less,  as  Hegel 
elsewhere  calls  it,  "  the  realm  of  shades."  It  is  necessary 
to  effect  an  entrance  into  this  realm,  notwithstanding,  nay, 
to  exj^lore  its  inmost  recesses,  in  order  to  attain  the  true 
speculative  insight,  for,  since  the  problem  of  all  science  is 
to  recognise  the  reason  on  the  several  planes  of  reality,  this 
problem  can  only  be  solved  by  knowing,  first  of  all,  what' 
reason  is  ? — and,  secondly,  how  to  find  it  ?  The  Logic 
teaches  what  the  Idea  or  the  Reason  is,  inasmuch  as  it 
exhausts  the  sum  of  its  determinations  as  they  are  pre- 
sented in  the  forms  of  abstract  thought ;  it  teaches  how  to 
find  the  Idea  or  the  Keason  in  so  far  as  it  is  a  doctrine  of 
method. 

The  Hegelian  Logic  falls  into  three  main  divisions : 
Doctrine  of  Being,  Doctrine  of  Essence,  and  Doctrine  of 
Concept.  "  The  Logical  has  three  sides,"  says  Hegel,  "the 
Abstract,  or  that  of  the  understanding ;  the  Dialectical,  or 
that  of  the  negative  reason ;  and  the  Speculative,  or  that 
of  the  positive  reason.  These  three  sides  do  not  constitute 
three  parts  of  logic,  but  are  the  momenta  of  every  logical 
real — that  is,  of  every  conception  or  truth  .  .  .  thought  as 

Y  2 


324  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

understanding  cleaves  to  fixed  determinateness,  and  to  its 
distinction  from  every  other  determinateness ;  such  a 
limited  abstraction  counts  with  the  understanding  for  an 
independent  existence."  "  The  dialectical  moment  is  the 
special  self-negation  of  such  finite  determinations  and  their 
transformation  into  their  opposite."  Just  as  the  previous 
abstract  or  affirmative  moment  is  the  classical  moment  for 
dogmatism,  the  mode  of  thought  characterised  by  hard  and 
fast  distinctions  and  one-sided  theories,  so  the  dialectical 
moment  is  the  classical  moment  for  scepticism,  the  mode 
of  thought  characterised  by  a  criticism  of  the  assumptions 
made  by  dogmatism  and  the  common  understanding,  having 
as  its  uj)shot  the  special  dogma  of  the  illusoriness  of  Keality 
and  the  vanity  of  Knowledge.  These  results  of  course 
ensue,  when  the  above  momenta  are  isolated  and  considered 
apart  from  their  connection  in  the  trichotomy,  or  system 
of  momenta. 

The  term  Dialectic  is  often  employed,  as  was  the  case 
with  the  Sophists  of  old,  to  denote  a  mere  barren  art 
of  confounding  an  opponent  by  an  appearance  of  con- 
tradiction which  does  not  really  exist.  In  the  Hegelian 
sense,  however,  Dialectic,  "  is  the  true  nature  of  the  under- 
standing's determination  of  things,  and  of  the  finite 
generally.  It  is  the  immanent  externalising,  wherein  the 
one-sidedness  and  limitation  of  the  understanding's  de- 
terminations presents  itself  as  what  it  is,  namely,  as  their 
negation.  It  is  the  nature  of  everything  finite  to  negate 
itself.  Dialectic  is  therefore  the  moving  soul  of  the  knowing 
process,  the  principle,  whereby  alone  immanent  connection 
and  necessity  enters  into  the  constitution  of  knowledge  ; 
and  whereby  the  true,  as  opposed  to  the  external,  trans- 
cendence of  the  finite  is  possible "  :  "  The  speculative  or 
•positive-rational  comj^rehends  the  unity  of  the  determinations 
in  their  opposition ;  the  affirmative  element,  which  is 
contained  therein,  is  their  dissolution  and  their  trans- 
formation. Dialectic  has  a  positive  result,  inasmuch  as  its 
result  has  a  determinate  content ;  inasmuch,  that  is,  as  its 
actual  issue  is  not  empty  abstract  nothing  but  the  negation 
of  certain  determinations,  which  are  nevertheless  contained 
in  the  result,  since  the  latter  is  not  mere  nothing,  but 
result.     This  rationality  therefore,  notwithstanding  that  it 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  325 

is  conceptual  and  abstract,  is  at  the  same  time  concrete, 
since  it  is  not  mere  formal  unity,  but  the  unity  of  deter- 
minations, which  are  clearly  distino-uished  as  such.  With 
mere  abstractions  philosophy  has  therefore  nothing  what- 
ever to  do ;  it  is  concerned  only  with  concrete  notions.  In 
speculative  Logic,  the  formal  Logic  of  the  understanding 
is  contained,  and  can  easily  be  separated  from  it ;  nothing 
more  is  required  for  this  than  to  eliminate  the  dialectical 
and  rational  element  therein ;  when  it  becomes  what 
ordinary  Logic  is,  namely,  the  summary  of  a  variety  of  co- 
ordinated thought-determinations  which,  although  finite, 
pass  for  something  infinite."  (Hegel's  EncyHopddie  der 
PhilosopMschen  WissenscJiaften  im  Grundrisse,  §  79-83.) 

The  first  division  of  the  Logic  treats  of  the  doctrine  of 
Being,  or  Consciousness  in  its  immediateness — the  concept 
in  itself — in  its  various  forms.  These  are  quality,  quan- 
tity, and  measure.  Quality  may  be  variously  considered  as 
being,  actuality,  for-itselfness ;  Quantity  as  pure  quantity, 
determined  quantum,  and  degree.  Measure  is  the  synthesis 
of  quality  and  quantity  ;  it  is  "  a  quantum  with  which  is 
combined  an  actuality  or  a  quality."  This  leads  to  the 
consideration  of  the  subject-matter  of  the  second  division 
which  treats  of  the  doctrine  of  Essence. 

Stated  briefly.  Essence  may  be  defined  as  Being  trans- 
lated into  appearance.  The  primary  momenta  of  Essence 
are  the  essence  as  ground  of  existence^  which  is  again  deter- 
mined as  "  pure  reflection  "  (identity,  difference,  and  cause) 
"  actuality  "  and  "  the  thing ;  "  the  phenomenon,  which  may 
be  reduced  to  the  "  world  as  phenomenon,"  "  content  and 
form,"  and  "  relation ; "  and,  lastly,  the  unity  of  "  re- 
flection "  and  the  "  phenomenon,"  reality  which  is  articu- 
lated as  "  substance  and  accident,"  "cause  and  effect"  and 
"  reciprocity  "  (action  and  reaction).  "  The  manifestation 
of  the  real,"  says  Hegel,  "  is  the  real  itself.  This  mani- 
festation is,  therefore,  essential,  and  is  only  so  far  essential 
as  it  is  in  immediate  external  actuality.  Previously  being 
and  actuality  have  appeared  as  forms  of  the  immediate; 
being  is  always  unreflected  immediateness  and  transi- 
tion .  .  •  The  real  is  the  positing  of  this  unity,  of  this 
relation  that  has  become  identical  with  itself;  it  is  there- 
fore rescued   from   transition^  and  its   energy  manifested 


326  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

as  externality ;  in  this  it  is  reflected  into  itself ;  its  actu- 
ality is  the  manifestation  of  itself  not  of  another."  The 
moment  of  reality  gathers  up,  so  to  speak,  into  itself  all 
previous  momenta ;  it  closes  the  circle.  The  highest 
catagory  of  the  Keal  is  that  of  reciprocity.  The  category 
of  reciprocity  indeed  carries  us  out  of  the  sphere  of  Essence 
into  that  of  Concept,  with  which  the  third  division  of  the 
Logic  is  concerned. 

^'he  concept  is  the  truth  of  Being  and  of  Essence,  and 
the  system  of  its  momenta  constitutes  the  totality  of  all 
determinations  of  Consciousness.  The  forms  of  the  con- 
cept Hegel  terms,  "  the  living  spirit  of  the  Eeal,"  the 
truth  of  the  Eeal  being  given  in  and  by  these  forms. 
The  leading  momenta  of  the  Concept  are  the  subjective 
concept,  which  embraces  the  forms  of  Logic,  the  object, 
which  gives  the  cosmical  notions  of  Mechanism,  Chemistry, 
and  Teleology,  and  the  Idea  in  its  totality  and  complete- 
ness, which  sums  up  the  whole  of  the  Logic.  The  Idea 
as  such  may  be  viewed  in  its  immediate  form  as  life; 
in  its  reflected  form,  as  knowledge;  and  in  its  absolute 
form,  as  unity  of  subject  and  object,  or  rather  as  the 
"object,"  to  employ  Hegel's  language,  "in  which  all 
determinations  are  concentrated."  The  Idea  in  this  sense  is 
absolute  truth,  the  ultimate  end  of  Philosophy.  The 
absolute  Idea  is  the  ^^  pure  form  of  the  Concept  which 
contemplates  its  content  as  itself."  This  content,  it  is 
scarcely  necessary  to  say,  is  nothing  other  than  the  system 
of  the  momenta  of  Logic  which  we  have  just  been  con- 
sidering. The  general  form  of  the  Idea  is  expressed  in 
the  Dialectical  method  in  accordance  with  which  the 
momenta  are  deduced,  or  rather  which  is  the  instrument 
of  their  deduction.  It  may  be  useful  to  observe,  as  bear- 
ing on  the  historical  development  from  Kant  to  Hegel, 
that  the  first  division  of  the  Hegelian  Logic,  the  "  Doc- 
trine of  Being,"  in  which  the  mere  immediateness  of 
Eeality  is  discussed,  corresponds,  roughly  sj^eaking,  to 
Kant's  "Transcendental  iEsthetic;"  the  second  division, 
or  "  Doctrine  of  Essence "  in  which  the  reflected  forms 
which  enter  into  the  constitution  of  Eeality  are  dealt 
with,  corresponds  to  Kant's  "  Transcendental  Analytic  ;  " 
while  the  third  division,  or  Doctrine  of  Concept,  which 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  327 

treats  of  the  categories  superimposed  upon  tlie  synthesis 
of  the  immediate  Real  by  the  Keuson,  is  represented  in 
the  earlier  (critical)  philosophy,  by  the  Transcendental 
Dialectic. 

The  general  scheme  of  Hegel's  philosophy  of  nature  will 
best  be  understood  from  the  following  quotation  :  "  Nature,'* 
says  Hegel,  "  is  to  be  conceived  as  a  system  of  gradations,  of 
which  one  necessarily  proceeds  from  the  other,  and  the 
immediate  truth  of  which  is  that  from  which  it  res'-^ts ; 
this  is  not  to  be  understood  as  meaning  that  one  is  naturally 
generated  from  the  other,  the  process  only  taking  place  in 
the  Idea,  which  constitutes  the  innermost  ground  of  nature. 
The  metamorphosis  applies  only  to  the  Concept,  as  such, 
since  change  in  the  Concept  alone  constitutes  development. 
The  Concept  is  in  its  nature  partly  inward,  partly  existent 
as  the  living  individual ;  hence  to  the  latter  only  is 
existent  metamorphosis  limited."  {Encyclojpadie,  §  249.) 
This  passage,  and  the  one  which  immediately  follows  it, 
in  which  the  doctrine  of  evolution  conceived  as  natural 
process  in  order  of  time  is  combated,  exhibits  one  of  the 
most  unfortunate  blunders  into  which  Hegel  could  possibly 
have  fallen.  The  answer  of  the  Evolutionist,  even  without 
departing  from  Hegelian  principles,  to  Hegel's  diatribe  is 
obvious.  That  the  develoj^ment  which  Hegel  admits  to  take 
place  in  the  order  of  time  in  the  life  of  the  individual 
takes  place  on  a  larger  scale  in  the  life  of  the  world's 
history,  is  a  direct  deduction  from  experience,  as  real  in 
the  one  case  as  in  the  other,  and  no  amount  of  arbitrary 
dicta,  for  Hegel's  attitude  in  this  matter  is  purely  arbitrary, 
will  deprive  it  of  its  reality. 

Notwithstanding  this  gratuitously  fallacious  assumption, 
Hegel's  "  Philosophy  of  Nature  "  contains  some  valuable 
insights,  though,  on  the  whole,  it  is  the  least  original 
portion  of  his  work,  being  borrowed  largely  from  Rebel- 
ling. Following  Schelling,  Hegel  divides  "  Philosophy  of 
Nature  "  into  Mechanic,  Physic,  and  the  synthesis  of  these. 
Organic.  In  nature  the  Idea  or  the  Absolute,  which  the 
Logic  has  treated  of  in  itself,  is  exhibited  in  the  form  of 
external  existence,  of  a  determinate  order.  Nature  is  the 
mediation  ( Vermittlung')  by  which  consciousness  comes  to  a 
knowledge  of  itself,  and  may  thus  be  regarded  as  zjjso  facto 


328  MODEKN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

the  out-of-itselfness  of  tlie  Idea  or  tHe  Eeason.  It  stands  in 
direct  opposition  to  tlie  Logic,  "  the  reahu  of  shades,"  as 
the  region  of  determinateness,  pa7'  excellence.  Hegel  allows 
his  impatience  at  the  fact  that  there  are  many  natural 
phenomena  not  yet  reduced  to  law  to  manifest  itself  in  the 
frequent  assertion,  that  nature  is  impotent  to  display 
rational  order  in  everything,  and  that  there  is  much  in 
nature  which  we  must  regard  as  pure  chance,  and  as 
destitute  of  any  philosophical  significance.  His  general 
attitude  naturally  leads  him  to  be  unjust  to  the  claims 
of  natural  science  and  its  representatives ;  against  Newton 
he  is  particularly  bitter,  though  this  is  perhaps  partly 
attributable  to  the  influence  of  Goethe.  The  main 
momenta  of  mechanics  are,  "  space  and  time,"  "  matter 
and  motion,"  and  their  synthesis  "  absolute  mechanic," 
in  which  matter  appears  as  a  completed  quantum.  This 
leads  us  to  the  second  division ;  qualified  matter  or 
Physic,  the  chief  momenta  of  which  are  the  physic  of 
"  universal  individuality,"  of  "  particular  individuality," 
and  of  "total  individuality,"  the  final  determination  of  the 
latter,  the  chemical  process,  forming  the  transition  to  the 
Organic  sphere,  the  stages  of  which  are  "  geological 
nature,"  "  vegetable  nature,"  and  the  "  animal  organism." 
With  the  consideration  of  the  animal  organism  we  are 
already  on  the  threshold  of  the  ^Dhilosophy  of  mind 
{Philosophie  des  Geistes),  i.e.  of  the  philosophy  of  Conscious- 
ness, no  longer  manifested  as  out-of-itself,  but  as  returned  in 
upon  itself. 

Hegel  closes  the  *'  Philosophy  of  Nature  "  with  some 
observations  on  the  death  of  the  individual.  "  His  incom- 
patibility with  the  universal,"  says  Hegel,  "  is  his  original 
bane  and  the  innate  germ  of  death.  The  abolition  of  this 
incompatibility  is  the  fulfilment  of  his  destiny.  Mind 
presupposes  nature,  the  truth  of  which  it  is.  In  this  truth 
nature  has  vanished,  and  mind  has  proclaimed  itself  as  the 
Idea  attained  to  for  itselfness,  for- which  the  concept  is  no 
less  object  than  subject.  This  Identity  is  Absolute  negativity, 
inasmuch  as,  in  nature,  the  Concept  has  completely 
manifested  its  objectivity,  but  in  mind  this  its  manifesta- 
tion is  abolished,  and  it  has  become  identical  with  itself 
{Encyclopddiey  §  381). 


ErocH  II.]  HEGEL.  329 

The  triple  division  of  the  "  Philosophy  of  Mind,"  is  as 
follows  :  first  of  all,  the  Subjective  Mind,  in  which  mind 
is  related  immediately  to  itself  as  the  ideal  totality, 
whose  being  is  freedom  ;  secondly,  the  Objective  Mind,  or 
mind  in  the  form  of  reality,  a  world  in  which  freedom  is 
reduced  to  necessity ;  and,  lastly.  Absolute  Mind,  which  is 
the  unit^T"  of  the  two  previous  momenta.  The  first  divi- 
sion embraces  "  Anthropology,"  "  Phenomenology,"  and 
"  Psychology,"  Hegel  only  employing  this  term  for  its 
concluding  section.  Psychology  considers  mind  theo- 
retically as  intelligence,  practically  as  will ;  and,  lastly, 
as  the  unity  of  these,  as  morality.  The  intelligence  finds 
itself  limited,  but  posits  this  very  limitation  as  its  own  in 
recognising  the  all,  as  realising  rational  purpose.  The 
essence  of  morality  is,  that  the  will  should  have  a  universal 
rational  content  for  its  purpose.  The  second  division, 
dealing  with  Objective  Mind,  shows  the  realised  product  of 
freewill  as  exhibited  in  law  and  right,  in  a  moral  code, 
and  in  social  institutions  culminating  in  the  state.  The 
Absolute  Mind,  with  which  the  third  and  last  division  is 
concerned,  is  determined  in  the  forms  of  Art,  Eeligion, 
and  Philosophy.  The  Idea,  as  the  Philosophic  Reason, 
forms  the  culmination  of  the  entire  system;  it  is  the 
Reason  come  to  a  knowledge  of  itself.  In  Art  it  is 
presented  to  sense,  in  Religion  to  the  reflective  under- 
standing, and  in  Philosophy  to  the  Reason,  which  pre- 
supposes yet  transcends  both. 

Such  is  a  brief  outline  of  the  Hegelian  system.  It  remains 
to  notice  briefly  the  working  out  of  the  several  depart- 
ments of  its  last  and  most  practically  important  division. 
Hegel's  Ethic  is  apparently  based  on  the  doctrine  of  freedom 
which  had  been  common  to  his  predecessors.  He  rehabi- 
litates Kant's  separation  of  the  legal  from  the  moral,  in 
admitting  a  sphere  in  which  the  individual  subject  is 
completely  controlled  by  the  objective  mind — in  short,  in 
which  its  freedom  is  reduced  to  necessity.  This  is  the 
second  of  the  cardinal  momenta  of  mind.  But  Hegel  does 
not  admit  law  to  be  a  limitation  of  freedom  ;  it  is  merely 
a  limitation  of  the  arbitrariness  of  the  individual  will. 
Nevertheless,  it  is  opposed  to  the  principle  on  which 
morality  rests,  which  is  conscience,  the  power  wherein 


^oO  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

good  is  combined  with  the  possibility  of  evil ;  both  of  these 
departments  are  however  one-sided,  and  are  united,  or  find 
their  synthesis  in  what  Hegel  terms  SittUchlceit,  a  word 
generally  identical  with  morality,  but  which  Hegel 
distinguishes  from  the  latter,  and  which,  employed  in  his 
sense,  may  perhaps  best  be  rendered  as  Virtue  (the  ancient 
civic  virtue),  the  Jjaiin  jnetas.  It  is  a  morality  with  a  definite 
social  content.  The  momenta  of  this  substance  or  content 
are,  the  family,  the  society,  the  state.  In  giving  the  highest 
place  to  social  obligation,  Hegel  shows  that  he  is  conscious 
of  the  barren  and  abstract  nature  of  the  Ethics  of  Kant 
and  Fichte,  for  whom  mere  subjective  freedom  was  the 
ultimate  goal.  By  this,  he  virtually  surrenders  the  stand- 
point of  the  "  ethics  of  inwardness,"  as  such,  together  with 
its  correlate,  the  "  religion  of  the  spirit,"  although  profess- 
ing to  have  placed  them  on  an  inexpugnable  footing.  The 
fact  that  he  finds  in  the  state  the  culmination  and  realisa- 
tion of  the  family  and  society,  rather  than  in  society  the 
realisation  of  the  family  and  the  state,  is,  however,  one  of 
those  strange  perversions  of  view  for  which,  we  fear,  w^e 
must  regard  governmental  patronage  as  largely  respon- 
sible. Both  logically  and  historically,  the  family  (or  rather 
the  gens)  is  clearly  negated  in  the  state,  the  tendency  of 
which,  qua  state,  must  invariably  be  to  abolish  the  ori- 
ginal independence  of  the  family.  The  complex  state- 
organization  is  the  antithesis  of  the  simple  family-organi- 
zation, which  it,  so  to  speak,  swallows  up.  It  is  plainly 
then  in  the  negation  of  the  state,  in  its  self-abolition,  in 
which  the  state  {cimtas)  is  transformed  into  a  free 
society,  a  higher  family-organization  (societas)^  that  the 
synthesis,  the  telos,  of  the  two  previous  momenta  is  dis- 
coverable. 

Hegel's  philosophy  of  history  is  in  accordance  with  a 
point  of  view  founded  on  the  conception  of  the  political 
moment  being  the  essential  one.  For  the  rest,  its  leading 
principle,  though  it  may  be  easily  inferred  from  the 
general  thought  of  the  system,  we  give  in  Hegel's  own 
words : — 

"  The  only  Thought  which  Philosophy  brings  with  it 
to  the  contemplation  of  history,  is  the  simple  conception 
of  Beason ;  that  Eeason  is  the  Sovereign  of  the  World ; 


Epoch  H.]  HEGEL.  331 

that  the  history  of  the  workl,  therefore,  presents  us  with 
a  rational  process.  This  conviction  and  intuition  is  a 
hvjiothesis  in  the  domain  of  history  as  such.  In  that  of 
Philosophy  it  is  no  hypothesis.  It  is  there  proved  by 
speculative  cop;nition  that  Reason  ...  is  Sahstanre  as  well 
as  Infinite  Power ;  its  own  Infinite  Material  underlying  all 
the  natural  and  spiritual  life  which  it  originates,  as  also 
the  Infinite  Form — that  which  sets  this  material  in  motion. 
On  the  one  hand.  Reason  is  the  substance  of  the  Universe  ; 
viz.,  that  by  which  and  in  which  all  reality  has  its  being 
and  subsistence.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  the  Infinite 
Energy  of  the  Universe  ;  since  Reason  is  not  so  powerless 
as  to  be  incapable  of  producing  anything  but  a  mere  ideal, 
a  mere  intention — having  its  place  outside  reality,  nobody 
knows  where  ;  something  separate  and  abstract,  in  the 
heads  of  certain  human  beings.  It  is  the  infinite  complex 
of  things,  their  entire  Essence  and  Truth.  It  is  its  own 
material  which  it  commits  to  its  own  Active  Energy  to 
work  up;  not  needing,  as  finite  action  does,  the  conditions 
of  an  external  material  of  given  means  from  which  it  may 
obtain  its  support,  and  the  objects  of  its  activity.  It 
supplies  its  own  nourishment,  and  is  the  object  of  its  own 
operations.  While  it  is  exclusively  its  own  basis  of  exist- 
ence, and  absolute  final  aim,  it  is  also  the  energizing 
power  realising  this  aim  ;  developing  it  not  only  in  the 
phenomena  of  the  natural,  but  also  of  the  Spiritual  Uni- 
verse— The  History  of  the  World.  That  this  "  Idea  "  or 
"  Reason  "  is  the  True,  the  Eternal,  the  absolutely  poiverful 
essence ;  that  it  reveals  itself  in  the  World  ...  is  the 
thesis  which,  as  we  have  said,  has  been  proved  in 
Philosophy,  and  is  here  regarded  as  demonstrated "  * 
(Hegel's  'Philosophy  of  History,'  Bohn's  edition,  pp. 
9-10). 

The  lectures  on  the  "Philosophy  of  History,"  consist 
mainly  in  disquisitions  on  the  various  forms  the  state  has 
assumed  in  the  different  historic  periods.  Social  and 
economic  conditions  are  of  course  viewed  as  completely 
subordinated  to  political.  In  his  younger  days  Hegel  had 
subscribed  to  the  revolutionary  views  of  Rousseau  and  of 

*  The  reader  will  have  no  difficulty  in  reading  between  the  lines  of 
the  theistic  or  pantheistic  colouring  of  this  passage. 


332  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

Ficlite,  but  at  tliis  time  he  had  no  expectations  of  patron- 
age from  the  Prussian  Government.  For  the  official 
philosopher  of  the  great  Bureaucratic  system  which  was 
centred  in  Berlin — a  system  the  perfection  of  whose  wisdom 
had  shown  itself  consummated  in  the  choice  of  its  philo- 
sophic representative — the  state  as  therein  embodied  could 
hardly  fail  to  express  the  highest  incarnation  of  the 
Reason.  The  extent  of  Hegel's  adoration  of  authority,  for 
its  own  sake,  will  be  estimated  when  we  inform  the 
reader  that  he  professed  to  regard  marriage  as  more  moral 
when  arranged  by  parents,  than  when  dictated  by  the 
inclinations  of  "  parties "  themselves ;  that,  like  Schel- 
ling,  he  was  prepared  to  apostrophize  the  Kaiser,  as 
the  political  "  soul  of  the  world ;  "  that  he  was  the  sworn 
defender  (and  this  on  grounds,  not  of  antiquarianism 
or  expediency,  but  of  principle)  of  monopolies,  closed 
corporations,  &c.  Erdmann  has  observed  that  Hegel's 
'  Philosophy  of  History '  combines  the  anthropological 
view  of  Herder,  according  to  which  humanity  passes 
through  four  stages,  with  the  political  view  of  Kant, 
according  to  which  the  Oriental  state  signifies  the  freedom 
of  one  alone  (despotism),  the  Classical  state  the  freedom  of 
some  (slave-holding  oligarchy),  the  Germanic  state  (presu- 
mably, as  represented  by  the  Prussian  system  before  '48) 
as  the  freedom  of  all  (?). 

Hegel's  lectures  on  ^Esthetic,  with  the  exception  of  the 
'  Philosophy  of  History,'  are  perhaps  the  most  popular 
of  his  works.  Hegel  felt  with  Schelling,  and  in  opi30sition 
to  Kant  and  Fichte,  that  the  moral  consciousness  was 
after  all  not  ultimate ;  that  there  was  a  region  in  which 
the  -individual  mind  was  freed  from  the  restlessness  of 
natural  and  moral  striving,  and  that  this  was  the  region 
of  Art  (compare  Schopenhauer,  supra,  pp.  296-9).  The  Art 
work  as  the  presentment  of  the  Beautiful  exhibits  the 
Absolute  in  sensuous  existence ;  it  is  an  appeal  to  the 
heart.  It  does  not  merely  afford  theoretical  knowledge 
or  practical  satisfaction,  but  it  raises  it  above  these  finite 
forms  to  a  sense  of  infinite  enjoyment. 

The  chief  periods  of  Art  are  the  Oriental,  the  Classical, 
and  the  Romantic.  In  Oriental  Art  the  special  characteristic 
of  which  is  symbolism,  the  matter  preponderates  over  the 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  833 

form;  in  Classical  Art,  the  characteristic  of  which  is 
grace,  the  form  and  the  matter  balance  each  other ;  in 
Eomantic  Art,  which  is  spiritual  par  excellence,  sublimity 
and  beauty  are  combined  ;  the /orm  asserts  its  pre-eminence. 
In  each  of  the  fine  Arts  these  momenta  are  discoverable 
no  less  than  in  the  Histoiy  of  Art  as  a  whole.  Thus,  in 
architecture,  the  art  which  is  first  in  the  order  of  time,  the 
moment  of  symbolism  or  sublimity  may  be  seen  in  the 
Monument  {e.g.  the  pyramid,  the  tower,  the  obelisk,  &c.) 
characteristic  of  the  ancient  Oriental  civilizations ;  the 
classical  moment  in  the  Greek  Temple  ;  the  romantic  in 
the  Gothic  Cathedral.  The  peculiarly  Eomantic  Arts  of 
Painting  and  Music  present  within  themselves  the  same 
stages  which  are  all  embraced  and  reduced  to  unity,  in  the 
Art  which  is  the  Art  of  Arts,  Art  par  excellence,  viz. 
Poetry.  Hegel  defines  the  form  of  the  Beautiful  as  the 
nnity  of  multiplicity.  The  progress  of  Art,  according  to 
Hegel,  consists  in  the  gradual  elimination  of  the  spacial 
and  material  element  therein.  The  beginning  of  Art 
Architecture,  exhibits,  as  above  stated,  an  enormous  pre- 
ponderance of  the  sensuous  material.  In  Sculpture,  the 
peculiarly  classical  Art,  the  mere  material  is  less  oi)tru- 
sive  ;  moreover,  as  embodying  a  definite  form,  that  of  the 
human  body,  it  is  a  step  towards  a  higher  ideality. 
Painting,  the  earlier  of  the  romantic  Arts,  the  perfection 
of  which  was  reached  in  the  middle  ages,  inasmuch  as  it 
gets  rid  of  the  third  dimension  of  matter,  implies  a 
further  advance  towards  the  ideal,  the  supremacy  of  form ; 
it  is  the  objective  art  of  form.  Music,  of  which  the 
material  is  pure  tone,  and  whose  perfection  has  been 
reached  in  the  modern  world,  finally  abolishes  the  element 
of  space  altogether;  its  content  is  the  inner  emotional 
nature,  and  hence  it  is  the  most  subjective  of  all  the  Arts. 
Lastly,  Poetry  dispenses  with  any  specific  material  what- 
ever, its  material  being  simply  language,  the  medium  for 
the  expression  of  thought  in  general,  and  Poetry  may  be 
truly  termed  the  Art  of  universal  expression.  It  compre- 
hends all  the  other  Arts  in  itself.  Painting  in  the  epos, 
Music  in  the  lyric,  and  the  unity  of  both  in  the  drama. 
It  is  peculiar  to  no  one  period  of  history,  but  is  present  in 
one  or  more  of  its  forms  in  all  periods. 


834  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

Hegel  showed  a  far  deeper  appreciation  of  the  significance 
of  Art  than  Schelling.  The  latter  could  merely  regard  it  as 
a  special  department  of  modern  culture,  and  the  artist  as  a 
professional  man  of  talent  or  genius  in  no  special  manner  the 
product  of  his  age  or  race.  Hegel,  on  the  contrary,  took 
an  historical  view;  he  saw  in  Art  the  expression  of  the  life 
of  a  period,  or  of  a  people  ;  he  saw  that  all  true  Art,  all 
Art  that  is  worth  anything,  is  essentially  social  and  not 
individual.  "  Each  generation  hands  its  beauty  on  to  the 
next ;  each  has  done  something  to  give  utterance  to  the 
universal  thought.  Those  said  to  have  genius,  have 
merely  acquired  the  particular  faculty  of  expressing  ihe 
general  social  forms  in  their  own  work,  some  in  this 
respect,  some  in  the  other.  Their  product  is  not  their 
invention  but  that  of  the  whole  nation  .  .  .  Each  adds 
his  stone  to  the  structure,  the  artist  among  the  rest,  only 
that  he  happens  to  have  the  fortune  to  come  last,  and  thus 
when  he  lays  his  stone  the  arch  is  self-supporting.  ' 

The  close  of  Hegel's  Philosophy  of  -3i]sthetics  as  usual 
contains  an  indication  of  the  next  division  of  the  philoso2:)hy 
of  Absolute  Mind,  viz.  that  of  Eeligion.  Religion  is  the 
form  in  which  the  Absolute  is  presented,  not  only  to  the 
perceptive  consciousness  or  feeling,  but  also  to  the 
reflective  understanding.  The  historical  momenta  of 
Eeligion  are,  the  nature-religions  in  which  God  is  regarded 
as  mere  natural  substance  (Fetichism  and  the  lower 
forms  of  Polytheism)  ;  those  Religions  in  which  the  Deity 
is  conceived  as  Subject  which  comprise  the  Jewish  Religion 
or  the  religion  of  sublimity,  the  Greek  Religion  or  the 
religion  of  beauty,  and  the  Roman  Religion  or  the  religion 
of  utility ;  and,  finally,  the  synthesis  of  nature-religion, 
and  of  subjective-religion,  viz.  Absolute  religion,  the 
ultimate  expression  of  which,  it  is  needless  to  say,  Hegel 
somehow  or  other  manages  to  find  in  the  special  form  of 
Protestant  Christianity  established  in  Prussia.  The 
dexterous  evolutions  performed  to  arrive  at  this  end  are 
more  curious  than  instructive;  especially  the  case  as 
regards  the  manner  in  wliich  the  leading  Christian  dogmas 
are  twisted  into  conformitj^  with  the  Hegelian  doctrine. 

As  Art  found  its  issue  in  Religion,  so  Religion  finds  its 
culmination  in  Philosophy.      Philosophy  is   truth  in  its 


Epoch  II.]  HEGEL.  335 

absohiteiiess,  the  thought  of  the  self-thinking  Idea,  of 
the  self-comprehending  Eeason.  The  development  of 
Philosophy  shows  a  progress  from  the  abstract  to  the 
concrete ;  the  philosophy  of  the  pre-Socratists,  of  the 
Eleatics,  of  Herakleitos,  and  of  the  Atomists  represents 
respectively  the  momenta  of  Being,  Becoming,  and  For- 
itselfness;  the  i^hilosophy  of  Plato,  the  categories  of 
Essence  ;  that  of  Aristotle,  those  of  the  Concept ;  that 
of  the  Neo-Platonists,  the  totality  of  the  Concrete  Idea. 
Similarly,  the  philosophy  of  the  middle  ages  and  of 
modern  times,  is  the  philosophy  of  the  Idea  as  self- 
conscious,  or  as  mind.  The  Cartesian  philosoj)hy  occupies 
the  standpoint  of  unreflective  consciousness  ;  the  Kantian, 
that  of  self-consciousness ;  the  Hegelian,  that  of  the 
Eeason  or  Absolute  knowledge.  Hegel  claims  therefore 
that,  in  his  system,  all  earlier  philosophies  are  implied 
and  embraced  as  essential  momenta,  at  the  same  time  that 
they  are  superseded. 

"  In  the  peculiar  form  of  external  history^''  he  says,  "  the 
origin  and  development  of  philosophy  is  presented  as  the 
history  of  this  science.  This  form  gives  to  the  Idea's 
stages  of  development,  the  appearance  of  accidental 
succession,  and  of  mere  diversity  of  principles,  with  their 
working  out  in  philosophical  systems.  But  the  craft- 
master  of  this  work  of  ages  is  the  one  living  spirit  whose 
thinking  nature  it  is  to  bring  what  it  is,  to  its  conscious- 
ness, and  immediately  this  has  become  object  to  have 
already  in  itself  attained  a  higher  stage,  a  stage  which  ig 
above  and  beyond  it.  The  History  of  Philosojphy  shows  us, 
in  a^^parently  diverse  philosophies,  on  the  one  hand,  only 
a  philosophy  at  different  stages  of  development,  and  on 
the  other,  only  the  special  principles,  one  of  which  under- 
lies one  sj^stem,  and  one  another,  but  which  are  only 
branches  of  one  and  the  same  whole.  The  last  philosophy 
in  the  order  of  time  is  the  result  of  all  previous  philoso- 
phies, and  must  hence  contain  the  principles  of  them  all ; 
it  is  therefore,  in  so  far  as  it  is  philosophy  at  all,  the 
most  developed,  the  richest,  and  the  most  concrete  of  all 
philosophies." 

Hegel  ianism  had  for  some  years  previous  to  the  death 
of  Hegel  in  1831,  overshadowed  the  intellectual  firmament 


836  MODEKN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

with  its  colossal  structure.  As  before  with  Kantianisin,  its 
parent,  so  now,  though  even  to  a  greater  extent,  with 
Hegelianism,  it  was  the  dominant  philosophy  taught 
throughout  Germany,  and  asserting  its  influence  in  all 
departments  of  culture.  The  term  of  Hegel's  life  coin- 
cided with  the  culmination  of  the  authority  of  his  school, 
and  the  C(jmmencement  of  its  decline,  considered  as  repre- 
senting a  system  one  and  indivisible,  as  the  doctrine 
of  the  master,  in  its  orthodox  form,  claimed  to  be. 
Soon  after  Hegel's  death,  his  disciples  published  his 
completed  works.  But  dissensions  speedily  became 
apparent.  The  first  crisis  in  the  school  occurred  about 
1835.  "The  school  of  Hegel,"  says'  Eosenkranz,  writing 
in  1844,  "  in  the  sense  that  others  must  seek  his  instruc- 
tion as  that  of  an  immortal  master  of  speculation,  not 
only  exists,  but  will  continue  to  exist  in  the  future,  just 
in  the  same  way  as  after  Aristotle  there  were  still  Aristo- 
telians, and  after  Spinoza,  Spinozists.  But  the  school,  in 
the  sense  of  a  social  union  of  disciples — in  the  sense,  that 
is,  of  a  kind  of  corporate  responsibility  of  one  Hegelian 
for  his  neighbour,  has  ceased.  The  Berlinerjalirhilcher,  its 
outward  meetlDg-place,  can  moreover  no  longer  be  con- 
sidered as  the  expression  of  the  development  of  the 
Hegelian  philosophy,  nor  as  the  organ  of  its  apologetics 
and  polemics.  The  most  violent  divergencies  of  disciples 
from  the  master,  as  well  as  of  disciples  from  each  other, 
have  become  notorious." 

This  break-up  of  the  school,  as  a  school,  Eosenkranz, 
although  himself  one  of  the  original  disciples  of  Hegel, 
justly  regards  as  inevitable,  and  indeed  as  a  hopeful 
reaction  against  the  worship  of  phrases,  and  of  the  system 
as  a  system,  towards  which  there  was  a  tendency  in  its 
halcyon  days.  The  collapse  of  the  Hegelian  school,  he 
asserts,  does  not  mean  the  collapse  of  the  Hegelian 
philosophy,  but  rather  the  necessary  condition  of  its 
continued  life  and  activity. 

There  is  a  passage  of  Hegel's  own  a-proj)os  of  this, 
which  is  worthy  of  being  inscribed  in  letters  of  gold,  and 
which  the  "  man  of  the  world," — who,  strong  in  his  smug 
ignorance  of  history  and  "  sound  common-sense,"  jeers  at 
the  internal   difterences  accompanying  the  growth  of  a 


Epoch  n.]  HEGEL.  337 

movement  as  signs  of  decay — would  do  well  to  remember : 
*'  A  party  shows  itself  to  have  won  the  victory  first  when 
it  has  broken  up  into  two  parties  ;  for  then  it  proves  that 
it  contains  in  itself  the  principle  with  which  at  first  it  had 
to  conflict,  and  thus  that  it  has  got  beyond  the  onesidedness 
which  was  incidental  to  its  earliest  expression.  The 
interest  which  formerly  divided  itself  between  it  and  that 
to  whicli  it  was  opposed,  now  falls  entirely  within  itself, 
and  the  opposing  principle  is  left  behind  and  forgotten, 
just  because  it  is  represented  by  one  of  the  sides  in  the 
new  controversy  which  now  occupies  the  minds  of  men. 
At  the  same  time,  it  is  to  be  observed  that  when  the 
old  principle  thus  reappears,  it  is  no  longer  what  it  was 
before,  for  it  is  changed  and  purified  by  the  higher 
element  into  which  it  is  now  taken  up.  In  this  point  of 
view,  that  discord  which  appears  at  first  to  be  a  lament- 
able breach  and  dissolution  of  the  unity  of  a  party,  is 
really  the  crowning  proof  of  its  success." 

The  success  of  Hegelianism  as  a  distinct  system  was  no 
doubt  partly  due  to  its  eclectic,  and  hence  to  some  extent 
conservative,  and  even  reactionary  tendencies.  Hegel 
restored  to  philosophy  in  a  new  form  what  Kant  had 
demolished  in  its  older  form,  viz.  Metaphysic  proper  or 
Ontology.  His  Logic  identified  "  Theory  of  Knowledge" 
and  Ontology  in  seeking  to  show  that  existence  was  only 
one  of  the  momenta  of  consciousness,  and  not  vice  versa. 
Again,  Hegel  had  sought  to  re-establish  a  modus  vivendi 
between  Theology  and  Philosophy  (albeit  at  the  cost 
of  the  former)  in  his  Beligionsphilosophie,  by  an  ingenious 
esoteric  interpretation  of  leading  dogmas,  and  also  by 
taking  under  his  wing  the  Prussian  Church  organization. 
But  Hegel  difiered  from  his  predecessors  on  a  most 
important  point,  the  practical  side  of  his  philosophy, 
to  wit,  the  virtual  surrender  of  the  individualistic 
Ethics  so  strongly  accentuated  by  Kant  and  Fichte,  and 
the  rehabilitation  of  the  ancient  conception  of  social 
virtue,  the  morality  which  has  for  its  end  the  family, 
the  city,  and  the  state.  That  he  was  led  to  this  partly 
by  his  zeal  on  behalf  of  Prussian  bureaucracy,  does  not 
alter  the  intrinsic  importance  of  the  change  of  stand- 
point.    With  the  events  consequent  on  the  revolutionary 

z 


338  MODEKN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  n. 

year,  1830,  the  conservative  side,  and  therewith  the 
system  as  a  system  of  the  Hegelian  philosophy  became 
shaken.  The  political  ascendency  of  the  middle  class, 
which  was  now  everywhere  the  order  of  the  day — the 
temporary  reaction  consequent  on  the  French  revolution 
havino'  spent  itself — ill  accorded  with  the  system  which, 
in  a  sense,  apotheosized  class-despotism  of  a  different  kind. 
Hegelianism  began  to  work  out  in  opposite  directions ;  a 
right  and  a  left  wing  formed  in  the  school ;  and  the  in- 
tellectual life  of  Germany  during  the  seventeen  years  from 
the  period  of  Hegel's  death  to  the  revolution  of  1848, 
is  mainly  taken  up  with  the  controversies  liberated  by 
the  dissolution  of  the  original  Hegelian  school,  which 
resulted  in  a  severe  struggle  between  the  various  sections 
of  the  party.  These  controversies,  religious,  social,  and 
political,  we  shall  briefly  notice  in  the  following  pages. 


The  Hegelian  School. 

Attacks  on  the  Hegelian  system  had  already  begun 
before  the  death  of  Hegel,  from  standpoints  which  were 
not  opposed  to  the  speculative  method  in  general.  Weisse, 
professor  of  Philosophy  at  Leipzig,  in  an  essay  on  the 
"  Present  Standpoint  of  Philosophical  Science,"  published 
in  1829,  criticised  the  Logic  in  a  theistic  sense,  and  subse- 
quently attacked  the  system  in  detail  in  a  series  of 
works.  The  Hegelian  right  consisted,  among  others,  of 
Gans,  Heinrichs,  Goschel,  Michelet,  Kosenkranz,  and 
Vischer.  These  men,  all  pupils  of  Hegel,  adhered  to  the 
doctrine,  more  or  less,  in  its  original  form,  though  for  the 
most  part  emphasising  the  conservative  side.  Michelet, 
who  is  still  living,  has  recently  published  a  summary 
of  the  system.  Of  these  more  orthodox  and  conservative 
disciples  of  Hegel,  there  is  little  to  be  said  in  a  work 
like  the  present,  save  that  they  took  an  active  -psui  in 
the  controversies  of  the  period. 

The  most  remarkable  development  of  the  Hegelian 
doctrine  was  that  accomplished  in  the  left  wing,  and 
which  is  associated  with  the  names  of  Strauss,  Feuerbach, 
Bruno  Bauer,  Ruge,  &c.     Hegelianism,  as   a  system,  at 


ErocH  II.]  THE   HEGELIAN  SCHOOL.  339 

once  tended  to  promote  and  to  check  the  free  tendencies 
of  the  age  in  Theology,  Politics,  Sec.    Its  most  noteworthy- 
product  in  Theology,  however,  was  the  ccleljrated  Tiibingen 
school  of  biblical  criticism,  the  best  known  names  connected 
with   which   are   Ferdinand   Christian  Baur,   and   David 
Friedrich  Strauss.     The  first  actual  crisis  in  the  Hegelian 
party  was   indeed   brought   about   by  the  publication  of 
Strauss's  Lehen  Jesii,  although,  considering  that  the  notion 
of  the  supernatural  in  Eeligion  and  History  had  been  practi- 
cally absent  from  the  educated  German  mind  since  Kant, 
it  is  difficult  to  understand  the  sensation  produced  by  the 
definite  working-out  of  a  "mythical   theory"  as   to  the 
origin   of  Christianity  by  Strauss.      But  the  main  issue 
in  the  religious  sphere  resolved  itself  into  the  question  of 
the  compatibility  of  the  Hegelian  system  with  theism  at 
all.     Hegel  himself  had  of  course  maintained  it  to  be  the 
only  possible  form  of  theism ;  but  this,  it  must  be  remem- 
bered, was  as  he  understood  theism.     He  also  (vide  supra^ 
p.  334)  affirmed  its  complete  accordance  with  Christian  doc- 
trine, as  established  in  Prussia,  again  with  the  important 
reservation,  however,    that   philosophy  was   to   interpret 
that   doctrine,  a  reservation  which  effectually  "kept  the 
word  of  promise  to  the  ear,"  but  as  effectually  broke  it  the 
hoj)e  of  the  orthodox.    So  with  the  theistic  question  ;  it  was 
not  long  before  the  more  advanced  Hegelians  made  u^^  their 
minds  to  expose  and  disavow  what  justly  seemed  to  them  a 
merely  verbal  accommodation.    In  Strauss's  second  great 
work,  the '  Christian  Dogmatics  in  their  Development,  and 
in  their  Conflict  with  Modern  Science,'  the  narrower  and 
the  wider  issue  were  brought  out  into  clear  relief,  and  the 
view  insisted  on  that  Christian  Eeligion  and  Modern  Philo- 
''•  sophy  are  opposed  to  one  another  as  Theism  to  Pantheism. 
There  is  a  sly  hit  at  the  master  where   Strauss,  playing 
upon  the  German  word   Grund  (ground  or  reason),  says 
that  a  jDhilosopher  may  have  very  good  grounds  (Griinde^ 
for  calling  himself  a  Christian,  but  he  can  have  no  reason 
[Grund).      To  the    philosopher,   for    whom   there    is    no 
^^\  lard    and    fast   distinction    between   this   and  the    other 
Kvorld,    for   whom    all     such    distinctions,  as    mind   and 
natter,  subject  and  object,  divine  and  natural,  are  at  once 
mbraced  and  transcended  in  a  higher  unity  there  is  no 

z  2 


340  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  H. 

greater  enemy  than  a  doctrine  which  affirms  and  perpetu- 
ates this  dualism  of  conception.  Inasmuch  as  the  resolution 
of  these  oppositions  has  already  accomplished  itself,  the 
criticism  of  dogma  becomes  identical  with  its  history. 
The  aim  of  Strauss  in  the  work  in  question  is  therefore  to 
point  out  the  precise  manner  in  which  the  ecclesiastical 
dogma  moulded  itself  out  of  the  biblical  doctrine ;  how 
with  the  Reformation  the  dissolution  began;  how  the 
tentative  doctrines  of  the  Eeformers  were  in  their  turn 
reformed  by  the  Socinians,  Sj^inoza,  and  the  English 
Deists  ;  how  the  conclusions  of  these  latter  were  pushed 
forward  by  the  French  and  German  Aufkldrung,  till 
Schelling  drew  and  Hegel  formulated  the  conclusion  that 
there  is  no  other  Divinity  than  the  thought  in  all  thinking 
beings  ;  no  Divine  attributes  other  than  natural  laws  ;  and 
that  the  All  knows  no  addition  and  no  diminution,  but  is 
continually  manifested  in  the  infinity  of  individuals. 

Bruno  Bauer,  who  originally  belonged  to  the  extreme 
right,  being  bitterly  attacked  as  a  representative  of  this 
direction  by  Strauss,  and  who  had  been  accused  of  being  on 
the  high  road  to  join  the  then  well-known  pietist,  Heng- 
stenberg,  startled  every  one,  when,  in  1839,  he  published 
his  "Herr  Doctor  Hengstenberg,  a  contribution  to  the 
critique  of  religious  consciousness,"  in  which  the  arti- 
fices of  the  orthodox  apologists  were  scathingly  exposed. 
In  a  subsequent  work,  the  notion  of  a  Church  organization 
is  treated  as  a  survival,  and  religion  declared  to  exist  only 
as  religiosity — that  is,  the  sentiment  of  devotion  to  a 
higher  power  ;  but  at  present,  Bauer  declared,  there  is  no 
power  to  which  the  individual  can  devote  himself  higher 
than  the  state.  Between  the  civil  and  the  antiquated 
ecclesiastical  organization  stands  Science  on  the  side  of  the 
former,  and  where  the  State  seeks  to  limit  Science  in  the 
interest  of  Theology,  it  is  really  fighting  against  itself. 

Bruno  Bauer  was  joined  later  on  by  his  brother  Edgar, 
who  put  forward  a  doctrine,  worked  out  in  a  meta- 
physical form  by  Max  Stirner,  of  whom  we  shall  speak 
presently,  which  may  be  regarded  as  the  prototype  of 
modern  Individualism.  It  proclaimed  the  individual 
supreme,  and  denounced  all  government  and  organizations 
whatever  as  destructive  of  the  individuality.  Thus  Bruno's 


EPOcm  n.]  THE   HEGELIAN   SCHOOL.  341 

divinity,  the  state,  was  nidely  swept  away.  Bruno  and 
Edgar  Bauer  were  alike  untiring  in  proclaiming  that  in 
the  individual  human  being  was  summed  up  all  truth  and 
all  reality. 

The  most  prominent  name  in  connection  with  this 
movement  was  that  of  Ludwig  Andreas  Feuerbach,  who 
was  undoubtedly  the  most  popular  exponent  of  the  in- 
dividualist and  empiricist  reaction  against  the  Hegelian 
Monism.  It  is  perhaps  hardly  fair  to  call  the  movement  a 
reaction,  for  strange  as  it  may  at  first  sight  seem,  it  was 
the  natural  working  out  of  one  of  the  sides  of  Hegel's 
doctrine.  Owing  to  the  very  synthetic  nature  of  that 
idoctrine,  it  only  required  a  very  slight  change  to  transform 
lit,  on  the  one  hand  into  pantheism,  and  on  the  other  into 
individualism.  The  moment  the  fundamental  point  of 
view  of  "  Theory  of  Knowledge  "  fell  out  of  sight,  and  to 
minds  which  could  see  in  the  distinctions  it  expresses,  mere 
word-jugglery,  absolute  individualism  was  the  necessary 
issue.  Of  course  subjective  Idealism  of  the  Leibnitzian 
type  must  have  been  the  inevitable  outcome  in  a  meta- 
physical point  of  view,  but  metaphysic  was  at  a  discount 
just  at  this  time,  and  in  consequence,  it  was  in  practical 
departments  rather  than  in  the  region  of  pure  speculation, 
"that  the  new  development  manifested  itself.  All  Feuer- 
'bach's  works  have  a  distinctly  practical  tendency ;  with 
roure  speculation  he  concerns  himself  little.  His  strength 
tties  in  negative  criticism.  The  salient  points  of  Feuer- 
Ibach's  theory  will  be  found  in  the  "  Essence  of  Christianity," 
tthe  English  translation  of  which,  by  George  Eliot,  is  well 
Iknown.  Bruno  Bauer  and  Feuerbach  were  naturally  in 
opposition  to  Strauss,  who  held  strongly  to  the  Pan- 
iiheistic  side  of  Hegelianism  ;  for  Strauss,  the  individual 
•mind  was  the  reflection  of  "  the  All,"  the  immanent  divine 
principle ;  for  Feuerbach,  the  divine  principle  was  simply 
•the  reflection  within  itself  of  the  individual  mind.  On 
ithe  political  side  the  difference  between  them  was  even 
more  accentuated— Strauss  was  the  Tory,  Feuerbach  and 
tthe  Brunos  were  Revolutionists.  In  a  small  hrochure^ 
entitled  *  The  Holy  Family  Bauer,'  the  eminent  Socialist 
writers,  Karl  Marx  and  Friedrich  En  gels,  criticised  the 
foregoing  writers  with  characteristic  humour. 


342  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

The  most  remarkable  product  albeit  tbe  reductio  ad 
absurdum  of  tlie  ex-Hegelian  individualists,  was  the  little 
work  of  Max  Stirner  (Dr.  Schmidt),  entitled  the  '  In- 
dividual and  His  Possession '  (Der  Einzige  und  sein 
Eigenthum),  in  which  the  author  seeks  to  show  the  heresy 
from  their  own  point  of  view,  even  of  Feuerbach  and  Bauer 
themselves ;  how,  that  is,  even  in  their  later  writings  the 
religious  principle  still  clings  to  them,  as  shown  in  their 
admission  of  the  Ideal  of  society  or  humanity  as  an  object 
of  devotion  for  the  individual.  "  The  Individual  and  His 
Property"  might  serve  as  a  text-book  for  our  modern 
individualist-anarchists.  The  principle  of  Individualism 
is  there  pushed  to  its  only  logical  conclusion.  The  "  self- 
consciousness  "  of  Bauer,  the  "  humanity  "  of  Feuerbach,  the 
*'  society  "  of  the  Communists,  are  all  stigmatised  as  relics 
of  superstition,  as  objects  of  worship.  From  these  stand- 
points, all  and  severally,  the  individual  as  such  is  lost 
sight  of,  and  yet  only  the  individual  is  real.  He  who 
devotes  himself  to  aught  outside  himself,  without  receiving 
an  equivalent  for  his  devotion,  surrenders  his  individuality 
— he  is  superstitious.  The  individual  Ego  is  the  only 
concrete,  all  else  is  abstract  and  unreal.  "  The  Ideal,  the 
Man,  is  realised  when  the  Christian  conception  becomes 
converted  into  the  proposition,  '  1  this  individual  am  the 
man.'  The  conceptual  question  '  what  is  the  man  ? '  has 
then  resolved  itself  into  the  personal  one  *  who  is  the  man  ? ' 
with  '  what '  the  conception  was  sought  to  be  realised ;  with 
*  who '  there  is  no  longer  any  more  question,  but  the  answer 
is  immediately  present  in  the  question,  the  question  answers 
itself  of  itself  ...  I  am  the  owner  of  my  power,  and  I  it 
is  who  know  myself  as  individual.  In  the  individual  this 
owner  returns  to  the  creative  nothing  out  of  which  he  was 
born.  Every  being  that  is  above  me,  be  it  God,  be  it  man, 
weakens  the  feeling  of  mj^  individuality,  and  pales  before 
the  sun  of  this  consciousness.  I  place  my  interest  in  my- 
self, the  individual ;  it  stands  then  on  the  same  footing  as 
its  transient  mortal  creator,  who  thus  feeds  upon  himself. 
I  may  therefore  say,  *  I  have  placed  my  interest  in  nothing'" 
(Der  Einzige  und,  sein  Eigenthum,  p.  491).  This  is 
certainly  a  novel  way  of  arriving  at  the  Stoic  "  apathy," 
for  such  is  practically  the  result  of  Max  Stirner's  reasoning, 


Epoch  H.]  THE  HEGELIAN  SCHOOL.  343 

as  will  be  apparent  from  tlie  concluding  sentences  of  his 
book,  which  we  have  jnst  quoted.  But  the  preposterous 
result,  and  much  besides  in  the  work,  which  is  merely 
paradoxical  and  bizarre,  does  not  detract  from  the  fact  of 
there  being  much  also  that  is  valuable  in  the  shape  of 
criticism  scattered  up  and  down  the  volume.  The  reply 
of  Feuerbach  to  this  attack  was  hardly  up  to  his  usual 
standard. 

The  chief  organ  of  the  Hegelian  left  at  this  period  was 
the  Hallesclien  JalirhiicJier,  the  editor  being  Arnold  Kuge, 
who  was  one  of  the  foremost  leaders  of  the  German  revolu- 
tionary movement  of  1848.  Unlike  Strauss,  the  Bauers, 
and  Feuerbach,  who  can  hardly  be  regarded  as  belonging 
to  the  Hegelian  school  at  all,  Ruge  was,  at  least  for  a  long 
time,  comparatively  orthodox  in  the  essentials  of  his 
Hegelianism ;  the  Jahrhilcher  nevertheless  formed  the 
general  meeting-ground  for  all  groujDS  of  the  party ;  and 
indeed  it  was  in  their  pages  that  some  of  the  earlier  essays 
of  Edgar  Bauer  appeared.  A  manifesto,  published  in  the 
year  1840,  by  Euge  and  his  co-editor,  Echtermeyer, 
nominally  on  "  Eomanticism  and  Protestantism,"  but 
which  was  really  a  thinly  veiled  political  essay,  had  a 
wide-reaching  influence  at  the  time. 

The  Jahrhilcher  now  began  to  directly  attack  the  old 
Hegelians  for  their  superstitious  reverence  for  the  master's 
doctrine,  as  well  as  for  their  political  indifferentism.  They 
were  accused  of  treating  the  Logic  as  a  kind  of  Veda,  while 
Euge  prophesied  the  rapidly  approaching  end  of  the 
kingdom  of  the  Hegelian  Brahma.  Hegel  himself  was 
vigorously  assailed  for  his  reactionism.  In  July  1841  the 
Halleschen  Jahrhilcher  appeared  as  the  Deutschen  Jahrhilcher, 
the  change  of  name  being  accompanied  by  a  declaration 
of  principles  in  which  the  strict  Hegelian  orthodoxy  was 
formally  renounced  in  its  threefold  character,  philosophic, 
religious,  and  political.  All  the  fetters  of  superstition, 
which  had  hitherto  clung  to  the  Jahrhilcher,  were  hence- 
forward to  be  discarded.  Henceforth  it  would  openly 
occupy  the  position  of  Strauss  and  Feuerbach  in  Theology, 
while  a  determined  war  was  to  be  waged  against  Feudalism 
in  all  its  surviving  forms.  The  great  merit  of  the 
Hegelian  philosophy  would  be  recognised  to  consist  in  its 


344  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  IL 

having  freed  men  from  traditional  prejudice.  The  time 
had  come,  Euge  declared,  in  a  subsequent  number,  when 
the  Church  should  become  the  School,  and  Liberalism  give 
place  to  Democracy.  The  publication  of  the  Jahrhiicher 
ceased  in  1843,  and  Ruge  repaired  to  Paris,  where,  in  con- 
junction with  Marx,  he  brought  out  a  few  numbers  of 
another  journal,  the  Deutschfranzosischen  Jahrhiicher.  Ee- 
turning  to  Saxony,  in  1846,  he  produced  his  third  venture, 
the  Beform^  and  sat  for  some  time  in  the  parliament  of 
Frankfort.  On  the  subsidence  of  the  revolutionary  move- 
ment, in  1850,  Euge  came  over  to  England,  where  he 
continued  to  reside  till  his  death,  which  occurred  at 
Brighton  early  in  the  year  1881.  Euge  is  unquestionably 
the  leading  figure  of  the  Hegelian  left  on  its  political  side, 
and,  as  already  observed,  on  the  dissolution  of  the  school 
practical  questions  assumed  a  more  and  more  exclusive 
importance. 

We  have  only  mentioned  a  few  of  the  more  striking 
names,  connected  with  this  period,  the  interest  of  which, 
from  a  purely  speculative  jooint  of  view,  is  secondary. 
With  the  revolution  of  1848  conditions  were  changed  ;  the 
Hegelian  school  was  finally  dissolved,  and  those  who  had 
constituted  it  were  scattered.  Among  the  surviving 
academical  "  monuments  "  of  the  older  Hegelianism  may  be 
mentioned,  Erdmann,  the  author  of  the  well-known 
*  History  of  Philosophy,'  professor  at  Halle ;  Kuno  Fischer, 
professor  at  Heidelberg,  and  Michelet  of  Berlin.  Hegel's 
pupil  and  biographer,  Eosenkranz,  died  in  1883. 


THE  DEVELOPMENT  FROM  KANT 
TO  HEGEL. 

KETROSPECT  AND  CRITICISM. 

We  have  now  reached  the  close  of  the  movement  inaiigTirated 
by  Kant,  and  therewith  the  close  of  the  History  of  Philo- 
sophy properly  so  called.  The  later  speculation,  that  is, 
such  as  is  subsequent  to  the  Hegelian  movement,  belongs 
to  current  thought,  and  cannot  as  yet  be  assigned  a  place 
in  history.  Of  this  we  shall  treat  in  the  following  and 
concluding  division  of  the  present  work.  Our  object  in 
this  section  is  to  take  a  general  survey  of  the  Kantian 
and  post-Kantian  movement,  and  to  endeavour  to  extract 
from  it  its  historical  meaning. 

Kant,  we  have  seen,  was  the  pioneer  of  a  line  of  specu- 
lative thought,  which  restored  to  philosophy  the  larger 
basis  it  had  occupied  under  the  ancients,  by  re-opening 
those  wider  issues,  which  had  furnished  the  themes  of 
the  treatises  of  Plato  and  Aristotle,  issues  which  form  part 
of  one  problem — that  as  to  the  meaning  and  constitution 
of  reality.  We  have  noted  how  Kant's  simple  psycho- 
logical query.  How  are  synthetic  propositions  a  priori 
possible?  directly  involved  the  question,  How  is  ex- 
perience itself  possible  ?  and  how  this  brought  us  back 
to  the  fundamental  inquiry  of  philosophy.  The  order 
in  which  Kant  discusses  this  problem  in  the  '  Critique,' 
and  elsewhere,  was  immediately  determined  by  the 
course  of  his  own  thought.  The  key  to  the  whole  is 
however,  to  be  found  in  the  deduction  of  the  categories 
from  the  ultimate  unity  of  apperception  or  consciousness. 
The  question  now  arises.  Is  this  thought-unity  from  which 
Kant  starts  really  ultimate  ?  Is  the  ultimate  form  of  the 
category  absolute  ?  Is  pure  thought  subject?  Does  not  con- 
sciousness presuppose  that  which  becomes  conscious  ?   In  other 


346  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

words,  Is  not  tlie  "  I  think  "  itself  susceptible  of  further 
analysis  ?  Is  not  this  ultimate  I  distinguishable  from  its 
thinking  ?  *  We  believe  it  is,  and  that  the  treatment  of  this 
principle  as  final,  and  as  a  purely  logical  or  formal  unity, 
is  the  origin  of  the  tendency  in  speculation  hitherto,  even 
where  professing  to  be  most  synthetic,  to  become  onesided. 

The  synthetic  unity  of  the  consciousness,  the  logical 
element,  presupposes  the  alogical  element,  the  J,  or  the 
principle,  which  becomes  unified.  This  principle  which, 
considered  per  se,  consciousness  or  knowledge  itself  presup- 
poses, may  hence  be  regard  as  the  matter  of  which  thought 
or  consciousness  is  the  form.  Now  we  contend  that  this 
ultimate,  all-penetrating  material  moment — the  subject 
as  such — has  been  ignored  by  most  of  the  leaders  of  specu- 
lation from  Plato  to  Hegel,  and  an  appearance  of  having 
transcended  the  distinction  been  obtained  by  the  hypos- 
tasis of  form.  At  first  sight  this  may  seem  a  subtlety 
which  can  have  very  little  speculative,  and  certainly  no 
practical,  importance  ;  but  we  shall  endeavour  to  show  that 
it  does,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  give  a  colouring  to  the  whole 
course  of  thought,  being  the  general  speculative  expression 
of  an  entire  code  of  ideas ;  and  that  the  antagonism  of 
Materialism  and  Idealism,  using  these  terms  in  their  widest 
sense,  is  involved  in  it.  In  the  speculative  or  generic 
method,  which  deals  with  a  process  out  of  relation  to  time, 
the  starting-point  is  also  the  goal,  the  beginning  and  the 
end  meet  as  in  a  circle.  The  ultimate  principle  which  in- 
volves and  includes  all  others  is  necessarily  the  determinant 
of  the  entire  system  of  principles.  Hence,  whether  that 
ultimate  principle  be  formal  or  material,  logical  or  alogical,! 
makes  a  profound  difference,  and  decides  indeed  the  whole 
character  of  the  system. 

In  Plato,  what  we  are  here  contending  for,  is  very  plainly 

*  Descartes,  in  his  famous  Cogito,  gave  modern  speculation  at  starting 
a  formalist  impulse.     (See  p.  146,  supra.) 

t  The  word  '*  alogical,"  it  has  been  suggested  to  me  is  objectionable, 
as  conveying  the  idea  of  an  "  unknowable,"  a  "  surd  "  outside  the  system 
of  experience  rather  than  an  element  therein.  The  terms  "positive 
logical"  and  "negative  logical,"  might  be  substituted  for  "logical" 
and  "  alogical,"  though  we  venture  to  think  the  context  will  preclude 
misconception  on  this  head. 


ErocH  II.]  KANT  TO   HEGEL.  347 

exhibited.  The  iinifyiiip;  tJiought-form  the  logos  is  abstracted 
from  its  alogical  matter,  the  Hylc,  and  hypostasized  through- 
out, as  the  system  of  Ideas,  which  reaches  its  cuhuination 
in  the  all-embracing  supreme  Idea.  Aristotle  lights  upon 
the  abstraction  .so  glaringly  and  consistently  carried  out 
b}'  Plato  and  energetically  denounces  him  for  it.  But, 
nevertheless,  Aristotle  himself  falls  into  substantially  the 
same  attitude.  For  him  also  pure  form — in  other  words, 
the  Ideal,  the  '  creative  intellect,'  as  actus  purus — was 
the  determining  element — the  all-embracing  fact — in  the 
constitution  of  the  real.  All  systems  founded  on  Plato 
and  Aristotle  exhibit  the  same  tendency,  that  namely,  to 
the  hypostasis  of  the  pure  form  of  consciousness  and 
a  fortiori  of  Thought  or  the  Ideal  as  such. 

We  pass  over  those  lines  of  development,  such  as  the  Dog- 
matic and  the  Empirical,  in  which,  since  they  are  not  based 
on  speculative  or  transcendental  analysis,  the  abstraction 
in  question  is  not  so  obvious,  or  so  easily  pointed  out  in  a 
few  words ;  and  coming  to  Kant,  who  re-affirmed  the  analysis 
of  experience  or  reality  as  the  first  problem  of  philosophy, 
we  find  the  same  abstraction  made  at  starting,*  the 
abstraction  namely  of  the  form  of  knowing,  or  thinking 
from  its  matter,  the  alogical  subject  which  it  presupposes, 
and  whose  self-determination  thought  is.  Fichte,  at  first 
sight,  appears  to  adopt  a  more  concrete  standpoint.  This 
is  even  confirmed,  as  it  would  Seem  by  certain  statements 
and  certain  portions  of  his  analysis.  But  when  the 
system  is  viewed  as  a  whole  (not  to  speak  of  reiterated 
assertions  to  the  same  effect),  it  is  seen  that  experience 
with  Fichte,  no  less  than  with  Kant  (in  his  transcendental 
deduction),  is  analysed  only  into  the  formal  unity  of  con- 
sciousness, that  Fichte's  "  ego  "  is  pure  thought,  and  not 
that  which  thinks  and  which  is  the  possibility  of  thought. 
The  moment  of  actual  self-consciousness  is  the  determining 
moment  of  the  whole.  To  Schelling  the  same  remarks 
apply,  at  least  as  far  as  the  earlier  form  of  his  system  is  con- 
cerned ;.  the  synthetic  unity  of  apperception  in  Schelling's 
system   appears   as   the  formal    indifference    or   identity 

*  As  regards  this , it  must  be  remembered,  however,  that  the  deduction 
of  the  categories,  with  Kant  himself,  only  concerned  one  side  of  his 
system. 


348  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  U. 

between  subject  and  object.  There  are  modes  of  state- 
ment in  Schelling  as  there  are  in  Fichte,  which  would 
seem  to  indicate  that  they  had  a  presentiment  of  the 
abstraction  involved  in  the  procedure  which  they  had 
inherited  from  Kant.  But  these  were  not  strong  enough 
to  alter  the  fundamental  character  of  their  systems.  Their 
ultimate  principle  remained  self-consciousness,  that  is, 
not  the  Ego,  but  the  Ego's  consciousness  of  itself.  They 
w^ere  formal,  and  abstractly  Idealistic. 

The  principle  which  Fichte  and  Schelling  were  vaguely 
cognisant  of,  but  the  real  bearing  of  which  they  failed  to 
grasp,  was  seized  by  Schopenhauer,  and  placed  in  the  fore- 
front of  his  philosophy  under  the  name  of  Will.  We  do 
not  of  course  mean  to  imply  that  Schopenhauer  was  led  to  his 
principle  by  a  systematically  reasoned-out  conception  of  the 
defect  of  his  predecessors,  or  that  it  adequately  supplies 
those  defects.  Schopenhauer  was  more  the  man  of  letters 
than  the  exact  thinker,  and  his  "  Will- to-live  "  was  rather  a 
poetical  expression  than  a  result  arrived  at  by  any  strict 
process  of  analysis  ;  but  his  system  embodies  unmistakably 
among  other  things  a  protest  against  formalistic  Idealism. 
This  explains  the  favour  with  which  he  regards  all 
materialistic  views  of  the  universe.  Schopenhauer  felt  that 
in  pure  thought,  considered  per  se,  there  was  no  dynamic 
'principle;  that  the  categories  of  consciousness,  even  the 
highest,  did  not  of  themselves  constitute  reality,  but  pre- 
supposed a  matter — a  subject — of  which  they  were  the 
determinations.  Essentially  the  same  revolt  against  the 
formalism  of  the  thinkers  in  the  direct  line  of  development 
from  Kant  underlies,  as  we  take  it,  the  system  of  Herbart. 
The  consciousness  of  the  purely  formal  nature  of  thought 
pel-  se,  it  is  only  fair  to  remember,  also  underlies  Kant's  own 
distinction  between  Sense  and  Understanding.  The  ele- 
ment of  feeling  was  to  Kant  as  necessary  to  the  constitu- 
tion of  Reality  as  thought  itself.  It  is  also  expressed 
in  his  distinction  between  Thing-in-itself  and  Phenomenon, 
at  least  in  one  of  its  aspects. 

The  encyclopedic  mind  of  Hegel,  with  its  Titanic 
grasp  of  method,  could  hardly  be  oblivious  of  the  fact 
we  are  here  pointing  out,  leaving  its  track,  as  it  does, 
throughout  the  whole  history  of  Philosophy.     But  Hegel 


KrocH  II.]  KANT  TO  HEGEL.  349 

evades,  in  his  own  case,  the  obviousness  of  the  formal 
nature  of  the  standpoint  he  occupies  in  common  with  his 
predecessors,  at  least  as  regards  the  working-out  of  his 
system  by  his  dexterous  manipulation  of  terminology. 
But  it  only  requires  the  most  cursory  glance  to  see  that 
thfe  taint  of  Idealistic  formalism  pervades  the  whole 
Hegelian  construction.  With  Hegel,  the  Concept  or  the 
Idea — pure  consciousness — is  the  totality  of  the  Real.  This 
alone  is  the  sharpest  and  most  distinct  pronouncement  of 
Thought  as  the  prtus  of  the  world-order.  The  way  in 
which  Hegel  covers  up  his  formalism  is  ingenious,  but 
hardly  convincing.  Let  us  take  as  an  instance,  the  passages 
on  page  29  of  the  '  Encyclopedia,'  where  Hegel  defines 
the  Ego  as  "  the  universal  in  and  for  itself; "  and  again 
as  "  pure  self-reference,"  "  the  abstract  universal "  *'  the 
abstractly  free,"  &c.  Hegel  here  refers  to  the  synthetic 
nnity  of  apperception,  the  universal  form — consciousness, 
which  is,  as  he  insists,  formal  and  abstract ;  but  in  this  he 
clearly  ignores  that  from  which  it  is  abstracted,  the  "  self  '* 
of  the  "reference,"  the  I  which  determines  itself  as 
thinhing. 

In  his  anxiety  to  grasp  the  whatness  of  experience,  he  let 
go  the  thatness.  The  Hegelian  would,  of  course,  reply  that 
the  fact  referred  to,  inasmuch  as  it  represents  the  possibility 
of  consciousness,  that  its  whole  positive  determination  is 
exhausted  in  being  the  possibility  of  consciousness,  it  is 
legitimate  to  regard  merely  as  one  of  the  momenta  of  con- 
sciousness. To  this  we  reply,  that  such  a  treatment  in- 
volves hypostasis,  a  seizure  of  the  formal  instead  of  the 
material  moment  as  the  primal  determinate  of  the  realy 
which  although  it  matters  little  in  pure  speculation, 
amounting  to  little  beyond  a  difference  of  emphasis, 
has  important  consequences  when  carried  out  in  more 
concrete  spheres.  The  difference  may  be  compared  to  two 
lines  gradually  diverging  from  one  starting-point.  At  first 
the  space  between  them  is  scarcely  discernible,  but  the 
end  shows  a  wide  discrepancy. 

Mere  subtle  refinement,  as  it  seems,  this  distinction 
between  the  absoluteness  of  the  actual,  formal  moment,  or 
consciousness  itself,  and  of  the  possible,  material  moment, 
or  that  which  is  conscious,  that  which  thinks,  reappears,  as 


350  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY.  [Epoch  II. 

already  indicated,  on  another  plane  in  the  distinction 
between  the  Idealist  and  Materialist  views  of  the  universe. 
As  a  natural  consequence,  the  Ethical  problem  of  free-will 
and  necessity,  of  determination  from  within  or  without 
the  empirically-conscious  personality,  hinges  largely  upon 
this.  That  man  is  able  consciously  to  determine  his  actions 
is  the  theory  of  free-will ;  that  his  empirical  conscious- 
ness merely  registers  a  determination,  of  which  it  is  not 
productive,  is  the  doctrine  of  necessity  as  now  understood. 
If  the  real  be  simply  a  system  of  logical  determinations 
alone,  if  its  totality  is  exhausted  in  the  Logical ;  if  in  its 
leading  momenta,  the  formal  is  their  determining  side; 
then  the  philosophical-theistic,  and  free-will  theory  of 
the  Hegelians  of  the  right  is  established  ;  if  on  the  other 
hand,  consciousness  is  not  creative ;  if  the  Logical  neces- 
sarily involves  an  alogical  element,  and  it  is  this  alogical 
element  which  determines,  which  is  the  8wa/x.i9  in  the 
production  of  the  experienced  world,  then  we  have  dis- 
covered the  root-meaning  of  the  protest  of  the  left  wing 
of  the  Hegelian  school  against  the  theistic  and  ideal- 
istic guise  in  which  the  doctrine  was  presented  by  the 
conservative  side. 

Hitherto  in  all  synthetic  systems  of  philosophy  it  is 
the  moment  of  form  of  limitation,  oi  for-itselfness  which  has 
dominated  the  whole ;  it  has  been  made  both  telos  and 
dynamis.  For  Plato,  it  was  the  Ideas  which  informed  the 
unreal  matter  of  the  sense- w^orld.  For  Aristotle,  again  the 
logos,  the  entelecheia,  was  the  determining  principle  of  the 
Hyle.  For  Hegel  lastly  the  formal  moment  was  absolute 
exjDlicitly  ;  the  Concept  was  self-existent. 

But  from  another  point  of  view,  the  matter  may  be 
regarded  as  self-determining,  and  the  form  as  its  self- 
determination  ?  The  hypostasis  of  the  formal  moment 
which  has  so  long  dominated  the  speculative  world 
then  disappears.  The  ultimate  principle  of  "  Theory  of 
Knowledge,"  or  philosophy,  the  science  which. alone  deals 
with  firs,t  principles  properly  so-called,  is  no  longer 
"  Consciousness,"  or  thought  as  such,  but  the  alogical 
subject  which  determines  itself  as  conscious,  which  is  the 
materia  prima  of  consciousness.  A  little  reflection,  we 
think,  will   enable   the   student   to   see  that  this  initial 


Epoch  n.]  KANT  TO  HEGEL.  851 

chan<:^o  of  attitude  shifts  (so  to  speak)  onr  point  of  view 
throughout  every  department  of  thought.  The  material 
rather  than  the  formal  heneeforth  becomes  the  determining 
moment  in  the  synthesis  of  all  and  every  reality.'^ 

*'  Thus  nature  is  self-determining  {jnd  not  determined  ah  extra  by 
its  mere  formal  moment  which  constitutes  what  we  term  "natural 
law." 


352  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY. 


RECENT  AND  CDEEENT  PHILOSOPHY, 


In  this  concluding  portion  of  the  handbook,  we  propose  to 
consider  the  state  of  Philosophy  during  the  second  half  of 
the  nineteenth  century.  In  doing  so  we  shall  pass  over 
lightly  those  writers  whose  general  influence  and  impor- 
tance is  secondary  in  order,  to  afford  more  space  for  the 
exposition  of  the  views  of  men  who  may  be  regarded  as  in 
some  sense  leaders  of  contemporary  thought. 

Since  the  break  up  of  the  Hegelian  school,  Germany 
has  fallen  somewhat  into  the  background  in  the  matter 
of  speculation.  Philosophical  literature  pours  forth 
abundantly  from  the  press,  but  it  represents  for  the  most 
part  merely  the  survival  or  the  revival  of  older  standpoints, 
without  exhibiting  any  new  development.  The  views  of 
Herbart  and  of  Schopenhauer  have  met  ^\ith  amplification 
and  modification  at  the  hands  of  fluent  and  able  'v\Titers. 
As  representative  of  these  may  be  taken,  on  the  one  hand, 
Von  Hartmann,  and  on  the  other,  Lotze. 

Eduard  von  Hartmann  (born  1842,  at  Berlin)  claims 
to  be  the  reconciler  of  Hegel  and  Schopenhauer,  but 
is  really  in  all  essentials  the  follower  of  the  latter. 
In  his  leading  work,  '  The  Philosophy  of  the  Uncon- 
scious,' Hartmann  maintains  the  Spinozistic  thesis  of  an 
unconscious  Absolute,  with  the  dual  attribute  of  "Will  and 
Idea.  He  rejects  the  Dialectical  method,  and  claims  for  his 
philosophy  the  inductive  basis  of  physical  science.  "  Ac- 
cording to  Hegel,"  says  Hartmann,  "  only  the  Logical  the 
Idea  is  ultimate,  while  according  to  Schopenhauer,  the 
Alogical,  the  Will,  is  ultimate."  The  conception  of  the 
Absolute,  the  prius  of  all  reality,  as  including  both  Will  and 
Idea,  reconciles  the  antagonism  between  them.  "  It  is  the 
gi*eat  service,"  as  Hartmann  thinks  of  Schelling,  "  to  have 


Epoch  II.]  MODERN   rillLOSOPHY.  353 

shown  the  possibility  of  a  modus  vivendi  between  the  two 
standpoints."  Schelling,  however,  spoilt  the  fertility  of  his 
conception  by  coquetting  with  theology,  which  misled  him 
into  fantastic  qnasi-porsonifications  of  these  principles. 
Hartmann  will  know  of  no  distinction  between  the  method 
of  philosophy  and  that  of  physical  science  :  to  jDroceed  from 
the  known  to  its  as  yet  unknown  ground  of  explanation 
is  the  true  method  in  both  cases.  Hartmann's  exposition 
of  his  philosophy  falls  into  three  divisions,  headed  re- 
spectively, "  The  phenomenon  of  the  Unconscious  in 
corporeality;"  "the  Unconscious  in  the  human  mind;" 
and  "  the  metaphysic  of  the  Unconscious." 

In  the  first  two  divisions  Hartmann  seeks  to  sub- 
stantiate and  illustrate  his  fundamental  assumption  in 
the  regions  of  physiology  and  pathology ;  in  the  third, 
in  the  human  mind  and  in  society.  The  term  "  Conscious- 
ness "  with  Hartmann,  as  with  Schopenhauer,  means  the 
empirical  consciousness,  and  hence,  like  Schopenhauer, 
Hartmann  properly  insists  on  the  correlation  of  conscious- 
ness "^dth  cerebral  and  nervous  action.  But  although 
conscious  activity  (in  the  empirical  sense)  is  inseparable 
from  organic  function,  this  does  not  preclude  us  from 
regarding  unconscious  activity  of  a  subjective  nature  from 
being  the  sine  qua  non  of  brain-function  as  of  every  other 
material  process,  which  may  hence  be  regarded  as  its  pro- 
duct. This  "  unconscious  "  principle  of  Hartmann  is  not 
to  be  identified  with  Schopenhauer's  "Will."  Schopen- 
hauer, in  proclaiming  "  AVill  "  the  jprius  of  the  world-order, 
banished  Intelligence,  as  a  primary  principle,  altogether 
from  his  system.  This  was  the  weak  point,  according  to 
Hartmann,  in  his  doctrine,  for  Will  alone,  apart  from  In- 
telligence, as  the  basis  of  the  Eeal  can  furnish  no  rational 
explanation  of  the  experienced  world,  nor  a  fortiori  of  the 
final  purpose  of  such  a  world.  In  this  particular  the 
Hegelian  doctrine  of  the  Idea  or  the  Reason,  as  the  ultimate 
principle  of  Eeality,  has  the  advantage  over  the  doctrine 
3f  Schopenhauer;  but  Hegel,  on  his  side,  is  unable  to 
explain  the  irrational  element  in  the  world-order,  which 
le  glosses  over  under  the  name  of  chance. 

I'he  true  inductive  method  which  Hartmann  claims  to 
ipply  to  speculation  reveals  to  us,  that  instinct,  i.e.  uncon- 

2  A 


351  MODERN   PHlLOSOrHY. 

scious  Will  in  inseparable  combination  with  nnconscions 
Intelligence  creates  the  world :  organic  and  animal  func- 
tions, arbitrary  and  reflex  motions,  sexual  love,  character, 
genius,  language  (in  its  origin),  nay,  conscious  thought  and 
perception  themselves,  are  all  reducible  to  manifestations 
of  an  unconscious  Will-Intelligence.  The  form,  the  adap- 
tability to  its  end  of  the  phenomenon,  shows  us  Intelligence ; 
the  ]Dhenomenon  itself  in  its  activity  shows  us  Will.  The 
conjunction  of  both,  Will,  which  is  jper  se  unintelligent, 
and  Idea  or  Intelligence,  which  is  per  se  powerless,  as  the 
dual  attribute  of  one  substance,  suffices  as  the  sole  ground 
of  ex^Dlanation  of  the  phenomenal  world.  The  absence  of 
the  principle  of  Intelligence  in  Schopenhauer's  system 
prevented  his  arriving  at  an  explanation  of  the  rationality 
displayed  in  the  order  of  the  world ;  the  absence  of  the 
motive  power.  Will,  prevents  Hegel  from  passing  out  of 
the  region  of  the  merely  logical  into  that  of  the  real  or  the 
existent.  The  conception  of  the  union  of  Will  and  Idea, 
of  the  realisation  of  the  logical  rational  Idea  by  the 
alogical  non-rational  Will,  reconciles  both  systems  by 
supplying  the  defective  element  in  them.  Now,  according 
to  Hartmann,  the  rational  is  real,  and  the  real  is  rational. 
The  rational  and  intelligent  order  in  the  real  is  expressed 
in  a  series  of  stages.  The  first  is  constituted  by  the 
simple,  attractive  and  repulsive  force-centres,  which  are 
the  foundation  of  the  corporeal  world.  They  are  the  first 
product  of  the  will-im]oregnated  Idea,  and  form  the  first 
rung  of  the  ladder  which  culminates  in  the  conscious 
organism.  Each  successive  step  expresses  a  victory  of  the 
Idea  over  the  Will,  of  Intelligence  over  blind  im23ulse  or 
force,  of  the  Logical  over  the  Alogical.  The  easiest  possible 
way  to  the  attainment  of  its  immediate  end  is  the  one 
chosen  by  the  Idea.  Thus  nature  prefers  to  bring  about 
improvement  in  species  by  *'  natural  selection,"  and  the 
*'  struggle  for  existence,"  rather  than  to  attain  the  same 
object  by  a  more  cumbersome,  even  though  a  less  wasteful 
method.  The  goal  of  this  w^orld-evolution  is  the  complete 
subjugation  of  the  (non-rational)  Will,  by  the  (rational) 
Intelligence.  But  the  complete  victory  of  the  Logical  over 
the  Alogical  presupposes  consciousness,  and  hence  the  pro- 
gressive series  of  being  in  the  order  of  evolution  gravitates 


IIARTMANN.  cJOO 

towards  one  point,  to  the  point,  viz.,  where  the  organism 
has  the  conditions  of  consciousness  complete  within 
itself.  This  completeness  is  first  attained  in  the  human 
brain  and  nerve  system.  Conseionsness  may  be  called  the 
final  emancipation  of  the  Intelligence  or  Keason  from  its 
bondage  to  the  Will. 

The  conscious  organism  once  given,  its  happiness  be- 
comes henceforth  the  more  or  less  immediate  purpose  of 
the  world ;  but  this  notion  of  happiness  is  an  illusion 
which  hides  from  us  the  higher  and  ultimate  end  of 
consciousness,  which  is  not  human  happiness,  but  the 
emancipation  of  the  world-principle.  Here  the  coinci- 
dence of  Hartmann  with  Schopenhauer  comes  into  view. 
To  Hartmann,  as  to  Schopenhauer,  existence  is  a  huge 
blunder.  The  more  intelligence  grows,  the  clearer  it 
becomes  that  the  pleasure  of  the  world  is  vastly  out- 
balanced by  the  pain  ;  and  this  applies  alike  to  the  indi- 
vidual life,  and  to  the  life  of  the  race.  A  crucial  instance 
of  it  is  afforded  by  a  comparison  of  the  amount  of  pleasure 
present  in  the  animal  which  eats,  as  compared  to  the 
amount  of  pain  present  in  the  animal  which  is  eaten.  In 
human  history  the  illusion  of  the  possibility  of  realising 
human  happiness  presents  itself  in  three  phases.  In  the 
classical  world  happiness  was  believed  to  be  attainable  in 
the  present  life  of  the  individual.  In  the  Christian  world 
happiness  is  believed  to  be  attainable  in  a  future  life  of 
the  individual.  This  belief,  which  modern  science  has 
shattered,  is  now  succeeded  by  the  third  phase  of  the 
illusion,  which  conceives  happiness  as  possible  in  the 
future  of  the  race.  Once  this  illusion  has  been  lived 
through,  the  truth  will  be  apparent ;  there  will  be  no 
room  for  any  further  illusion  as  to  the  possible  realisation 
of  happiness.  The  one  end  will  henceforth  be  Nirvana, 
though  not  the  Nirvana  of  Schopenhauer,  who  takes 
account  of  the  individual  merely,  and  not  of  the  race. 
The  quietism  which  Schopenhauer  preached  is  simply  a 
phase  of  the  Christian  religious  spirit.  There  is  no  short 
cut  to  Nirvana,  such  as  Schopenhauer  imagined,  attainable 
by  the  individual.  The  pietistic  results  of  Schopenhauer's 
philosophy  must  be  given  up  for  a  more  extended  view, 
which  shows  us  the  individual  as  powerless  to  arrest  the 

2  A  2 


356  MODERN    PHILOSOPHY. 

world-process,  which  exhibits  the  act  of  reminciation  as 
"brought  about  through  the  desire  of  happiness  having 
been,  in  the  natural  order  of  things,  quenched,  not  in  the 
individual  alone,  but  throughout  all  conscious  beings. 

Even  the  highest  of  all  pleasures,  literary  and  artistic 
activity,  in  this  third  stage  of  the  illusion  into  which  Ave 
are  njow  entering  begins  to  wear  itself  out.  All  tends  to  a 
low  level  of  mediocrity.  The  combination  of  selfishness  and 
sympathy,  which  sees  in  the  future  happiness  of  the  whole, 
a  reward  for  the  sacrifice  of  individual  well-being,  will 
have  had  its  day,  according  to  Hartmann,  when  wealth 
and  comfortable  circumstances — in  short,  all  that  can  be 
effected  alike  for  the  race  or  the  individual — is  seen  to  be 
of  no  lasting  value  in  producing  happiness,  and  this  expe- 
rience is  being  made  by  increasing  numbers  (?)  in  propor- 
tion to  the  spread  of  civilization.  This  on  the  one  hand. 
On  the  other,  the  teaching  of  experience  shows  us  that 
the  sum  of  actual  pain  in  no  wise  tends  to  diminish. 
Side  by  side  with  the  advance  of  medical  knowledge, 
illness,  more  especially  obscure  and  chronic  maladies, 
increase  in  greater  proportion.  Hunger  consumes  an  ever- 
widening  social  area  with  the  necessary  progress  of 
population.  "  The  most  contented  peoples  are  the  rude 
nature  races,  and  of  the  civilized  races,  the  uneducated 
classes ;  with  the  growing  culture  of  the  people,  grows,  as 
experience  shows  us,  discontent."  We  must  nevertheless, 
by  the  force  of  an  invincible  and  irresistible  destiny,  press 
on  along  the  road  which  inevitably  leads  to  the  dispersion 
of  our  most  cherished  hopes,  to  the  recognition  of  those 
hopes  as  illusions.  Nothing  will  be  left  then,  the  last 
illusion  having  vanished,  than  the  desire  for  euthanasia,  a 
painless  extinction.  "  The  Logical,"  says  Hartmann, 
"  directs  the  world-process  in  the  wisest  manner  towards  its 
goal — the  highest  possible  development  of  consciousness 
— which,  once  attained,  consciousness  sufSces  to  hurl  back 
the  whole  actual  Will  into  nothingness,  whereby  at  once 
the  process  and  the  world  comes  to  an  end  without  leaving 
so  much  as  a  fragment  behind  with  which  a  further  process 
could  begin.  Thus  the  Logical  constitutes  the  world  in 
the  best  possible  way  that  it  may  most  readily  attain  to 
emancipation,  and  not  in  one  whereby  its  pain  would  be 


HARTMANN.  357 

infinitely  perpetuated "  (Philosojphie  des  Unhewussten,  3id 
ed.,  p.  756). 

Wo  do  not  propose  to  attempt  any  detailed  criticism  of 
Hartmann's  system.  It  is  vulnerable  at  a  hundred  points. 
Ilartmann,  nevertheless,  has  a  significance  with  relation 
to  the  development  of  German  speculation,  and  this 
significance  consists  in  his  having  emphasised  the  dis- 
tinction already  alluded  to  between  the  point  of  view 
which  analj'ses  all  experience  into  logical  or  jyositive 
thought-determinations,  and  that  which  sees  in  the 
alogical  an  element  of  prior  necessity  to  the  logos.  This 
is  the  point  from  which  Hartmann's  metaphj^sic  starts. 
But  his  system  exhibits  a  hopeless  confusion  between  the 
spheres  of  "Theory  of  Knowledge,"  Physics,  and  Meta- 
physics, which  inevitably  leads  to  a  fantastic  semi-theo- 
sophicai  treatment  of  the  problem.  His  initial  rejection 
of  the  dialectical  method  and  nane  announcement  of  the 
attainment  of  speculative  results,  according  to  the  method 
of  natural  science,  many  will  think,  puts  the  subse- 
quent construction  out  of  court  at  once,  so  far  as  serious 
criticism  is  concerned.  The  "  Philosophy  of  the  Uncon- 
scious," and  indeed,  more  or  less,  all  Hartmann's  works  are 
without  doubt  suggestive,  and  apart  from  their  readable 
style,  they  will  well  repay  perusal.  Hartmann's  pessimism, 
which  has  descended  straight  from  Schopenhauer,  with, 
however,  the  not  unimportant  modification  already  men- 
tioned, is  one  of  the  most  natural  literary  expressions  of  the 
efiete  civilization  of  an  age  of  transition.  This  comes  out 
more  especially  when  Hartmann  criticises  the  jDresent  order 
of  society  with  its  dull  level  of  mediocrity  and  growing 
inequality  of  social  conditions,  as  though  it  represented 
the  final  stage  of  human  progress.  A  'part  at  least  of  his 
argument  in  the  cha2"»ter  on  the  third  stage  of  the  illusion, 
rests  upon  the  assumption  that  the  present  basis  of  society 
is  necessarily  permanent.  Hartmann  sees  that  things 
perforce  tend  from  bad  to  worse,  proceeding  on  current 
lines,  but  he  ignores  the  possibility  of  a  fundamental 
change  in  the  constitution  of  society,  and  therefore  of 
human  life  generalty.  The  all-degrading  black  coat  of 
the  Bourgeois,  covering,  as  it  does,  a  mental  and  physical 
constitution,  sodden   by  profit-mongering  in   its  various 


358  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY. 

phases,  it  does  not  seem  to  occur  to  Hartmann,  may 
possibly  account  for  his  pessimism  as  it  does  for  many 
other  things ;  and  that  pessimistic  views  of  the  universe 
may  pass  away  as  a  tale  that  is  told,  together  with  the 
aforesaid  black-coated  creature,  whom  he  justly  takes  as 
the  sign  and  symbol  of  universal  mediocrity. 

KuDOLPH  Hermann  Lotze  (bom  May  21,  1817,  died  July 
1st,  1881)  represents  another  phase  of  dogmatic  reaction 
against  the  formalism  of  Hegel.  Just  as  Hartmann's 
philosophy  is  a  following  out  of  the  doctrines  of  Schopen- 
hauer, so  Lotze's  may  be  considered  as  related  to  those  of 
Herbart,  though  the  connection  is,  perhaps,  not  so  close  in 
the  latter  as  in  the  former  case. 

Lotze  entirely  repudiates  the  dialectical  method  and  all 
speculation  immediately  based  on  that  method,  though 
without  on  the  other  hand  regarding  the  methods  of  physical 
science  as  in  themselves  ultimate.  To  understand  the  wait- 
ings of  Lotze,  of  which  '  The  Metaphysic '  and  '  The  Logic ' 
were  the  earliest,  though  the  '  Microcosmos  '  is  the  most 
important,  it  is  necessary  to  bear  in  mind  that  his  mind 
was  essentially  double-sided.  Possessed  of  a  consummate 
reverence  for  the  methods  of  physical  science,  he  had  an 
artistic  side  which  could  not  rest  satisfied  with  those 
methods  considered  as  final.  The  following  statement  of 
his  position  is  taken  froin  Herr  Merz's  article  "  Lotze,"  in  the 
'  Encyclopgedia  Britannica,'  9th  edition  :  "  Lotze's  definition 
of  philosophy  is  given,"  says  Herr  Merz,  "  after  his  expo- 
sition of  logic  has  established  two  points,  viz.  the  existence 
in  our  mind  of  certain  laws  and  forms  according  to  which 
we  connect  the  material  supplied  to  us  by  our  senses,  and, 
secondly,  the  fact  that  logical  thought  cannot  be  usefully 
employed  without  the  assumption  of  a  further  set  of 
connexions,  not  logically  necessary,  but  assumed  to  exist 
between  the  data  of  experience  and  observation.  These 
connexions  of  a  real,  not  formal,  character  are  handed  to  us 
by  the  separate  sciences,  and  by  the  usage  and  culture  of 
everyday  life.  Language  has  crystallized  them  into  certain 
definite  notions  and  expressions,  without  which  we  cannot 
go  a  single  step,  but  which  we  have  accepted  without 
knowing  their  exact  meaning,  much  less  their  origin.     In 


LOTZE.  359 

consequence  the  special  sciences  and  the  wisdom  of  common 
life  entangle  themselves  easily  and  frequently  in  contra- 
dictions. A  problem  of  a  purely  formal  character  thus 
presents  itself,  viz.  this — to  try  to  bring  unity  and 
harmony  into  the  scattered  thoughts  of  our  general  culture  ; 
to  trace  tlicm  to  their  primary  assumptions  and  follow 
them  to  their  ultimate  consequences ;  to  connect  them  all 
together ;  to  remodel,  curtail,  or  amplify  them,  so  as  to 
remove  their  apjoarent  contradictions,  and  to  combine  them 
in  the  unity  of  an  harmonious  view  of  things,  and  especially 
to  make  those  conceptions  from  which  the  single  sciences 
start  as  assumptions  the  object  of  research,  and  fix  the 
limits  of  their  applicability.  This  is  the  formal  definition 
of  philosophy.  Whether  an  harmonious  conception  thus 
gained  will  represent  more  than  an  agreement  among  our 
thoughts,  whether  it  will  represent  the  real  connexion  of 
things,  and  thus  possess  objective  not  merely  subjective 
value,  cannot  be  decided  at  the  outset.  It  is  also  un- 
warranted to  start  with  the  expectation  that  everything 
in  the  world  should  be  explained  by  one  principle,  and  it 
is  a  needless  restriction  of  our  means  to  expect  unity  of 
method." 

Lotze's  metaphysic  starts  with  an  examination  of 
causality,  and  the  categories,  in  accordance  with  his  defi- 
nition of  metaphysics,  as  the  same  which  has  for  its  objects 
of  investigation  those  conceptions  and  propositions  which 
in  ordinary  life  and  in  the  special  sciences  are  applied 
as  principles  of  investigation.  It  is  divided  into  Ontology, 
Cosmology,  and  Phenomenology. 

In  entering  upon  the  third  division  of  his  Methaphysic, 
Lotze  says  (Grimclzuge  der  Metaphysic,  §  26)  :  "  Ontologically 
we  have  spoken  of  the  '  essence  and  states  of  the  existent,' 
without  being  able  to  indicate  wherein  they  either  of  them 
properly  consisted.  Cosmologically,  we  have  assumed  that 
from  the.se  unknown  reciprc^cal  effects  of  things  proceeds 
for  us  the  perceptive  world  of  phenomena.  Finally,  at  the 
close  of  the  Cosmology,  requirements  of  the  mind  have 
made  themselves  apparent  which  presumably  are  only  to 
be  satisfied  hj  an  insight  into  the  real  nature  of  the  things 
which  constitutes  that  which  the  formal  conditions  of 
Ontology  and  Cosmology  demand.     Now  the  inner  states 


360  MODEEN   PHILOSOPHY. 

of  all  other  tilings  are  impenetrable  b}^  ns ;  only  those  of 
our  own  soul  which  we  regard  as  one  of  these  essences  do 
we  immediately  experience.  The  hope  arises  to  learn  by 
this  example  what  properly  constitutes  \h.Q  positive  essence 
of  other  things.  We  might  therefore  term  the  last 
section  of  the  Metaphysic  as  hithei  to  '  Pyschology,'  were 
it  not  that  the  soul  is  only  of  essential  interest  to  us  Jiere 
in  so  far  as  it  is  the  subject  of  knowledge." 

In  spite  of  his  repudiation  of  Herbartianism,  there  is  no 
thinker  from  whom  Lotze  has  borrowed  more  than  from 
Herbart.  The  method  formulated  by  Lotze,  that  of  the 
reduction  of  conceptions  to  distinctness  and  consistency, 
is  almost  identical  with  that  of  Herl^art.  The  extreme 
pluralism  of  Herbart  is  indeed  abandoned  in  favour  of 
what  is  in  essence,  a  kind  of  Spinozistic  Monism,  though 
it  subsequently  assumes  the  regulation  theistic  guise  led 
up  to  by  "  the  idea  of  the  Good."  As  its  result  Lotze's 
Metaphysic  gives  three  ultimate  ideas,  "(1)  that  of  one 
infinite  essence,  to  whose  necessity  the  ontology  points; 
(2)  that  which  we  have  developed  in  brief  that  all  true 
reality)  is  possible  only  in  the  form  of  spirituality ;  (3)  the 
one  just  indicated,  although  properly-speaking  indemon- 
strable by  metaphysic  itself,  that  the  highest  ground  for 
the  determination  of  the  world  and  of  our  metaphysical 
thoughts  thereupon  must  be  sought  in  the  idea  of  the 
highest  good." 

"  The  union  of  these  three  projDOsitions,"  continues 
Lotze,  "  gives  the  result  that  the  substantial  ground  of 
the  world  is  an  intelligence  whose  essence  our  cognition  can 
only  indicate  as  the  living  actual  good.  Everything  finite  is 
the  action  of  this  infinite.  Eeal  beings  are  those  of  its 
actions  which  it  continuously  maintains  as  the  active  and 
passive  centres  of  out-and-in-going  effects;  and  their 
'reality,'  that  is  the  relative  independence  accruing  to  them, 
consists  not  in  a  '  being  outside  the  infinite '  (which  no 
definition  can  make  clear),  but  only  therein  that  they 
are  for  themselves  as  spiritual  elements ;  this  for-itselfness 
is  the  real  in  that  which  we  inadequately  formulate  as 
'  being  outside  the  infinite.'  What  we  ordinarily  call 
'  things '  and  '  events,'  are  the  sum  of  those  other  actions 
which  the  highest  principle  in  all  minds  carries  out  in 


DUHRING.  361 

SO  systematic  and  orderly  a  connection  that  this  must 
appear  to  constitute  a  spacial  workl  of  substantial  and 
active  things.  But  the  meaning  of  the  universal  laws 
in  accordance  with  which  the  infinite  mind  proceeds  in 
the  creation,  maintenance,  and  regulation  of  this  apparent 
world  of  things  are  consequences  of  the  idea  of  the  good 
in  which  its  nature  consists."  (^Grundziige  der  ^letaphysic, 
§  94.) 

The  physiological  researches  of  Lotze  it  is  which  have 
given  him  his  position  in  the  world  of  thought.  There  is 
little  that  is  original  in  the  purely  philosophical  side  of  his 
speculation,  which,  after  all  is  said,  amount  to  no  more 
in  the  last  resort  than  a  quasi- Leibnitzian  Theism,  dressed 
up  with  results  derived  from  Fichte,  Schelling,  and  Hegel 
(albeit  the  speculative  method  b}"  which  those  results  are 
obtained,  and  in  the  light  of  which  they  alone  possess 
meaning  is  rejected),  and  last,  but  not  least,  of  Herbart. 
The  cleverness  with  which  these  ideas,  derived  from 
different  systems,  are  pieced  together  and  the  whole  made 
to  acquire  plausibility  by  being  dexterously  interwoven 
with  the  results  of  the  latest  scientific  research,  has  sufficed 
to  give  the  system  a  certain  importance,  which  it  would 
not  otherwise  possess,  in  current  i^hilosophical  literature. 
The  best  short  account  of  Lotze  is  that  given  by  Erdmann 
at  the  close  of  the  second  volume  of  his  history. 

Among  other  representatives  of  current  German  philo- 
sophy may  be  mentioned  Eugen  Duhring,  whose  standpoint, 
that  of  a  somewhat  crude  materialism,  is  worked  out  in"  his 
Cursus  der  Philosophie,  Duhring  attaches  a  high  value  to 
Comte  and  Feuerbach  as  well  as  to  Buckle  and  the 
English  empirical  thinkers,  with  the  exception  of  Herbert 
Spencer,  for  whom  he  has  a  profound  contempt. 

The  law  of  identity  is  the  ultimate  law  of  all  reality. 
(This  is  of  course  aimed  at  the  Hegelians. )  It  is  a  fallacy 
to  regard  the  conceptions  of  universality  and  law  as  ex- 
changeable ;  an  individual  fact  may  have  the  notion  of 
law  or  necessity  attaching  to  it.  Duhring  is  an  'Atomist. 
The  atom  is  the  ultimate  real.  The  complementary 
principle  to  matter  in  the  construction  of  reality  is  that 
of  change  and  permanence.     For  the  cause  of  the  primal 


862  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY. 

origin  of  motion  or  change  in  material  substance,  science 
is  at  present  unable  to  offer  any  satisfactory  account ;  this 
is  the  task  for  Mechanics  in  the  future.  Antagonistic 
motion  is  the  sole  method  of  progress.  Diihring  would 
explain  all  phenomena  on  strictly  mechanical  principles. 
Like  all  other  cosmic  processes,  feeling  is  reducible  to  the 
opposition  of  forces ;  all  feeling  involves  a  sense  of  resis- 
tance. In  sense-perception  nature,  so  to  say,  repeats  her- 
self, hence  the  natural  assumption  that  perception  corre- 
sponds to  objectivity  is  justified.  What  the  feelings  are 
for  knowledge,  the  emotions  are  for  action.  It  is  not, 
however,  in  his  philosopliy  proper  that  such  importance 
as  Diihring  possesses  is  to  be  found  ;  but  rather  in  his 
criticism  of  society  and  in  his  insights  into  the  future,  in 
which  he  has  borrowed  largely  from  Marx  and  Lasalle, 
whom  he  at  the  same  time  attacks  for  their  Hegelianism. 

We  must  not  omit  to  notice  also  the  eminent  author  of 
the  History  of  Materialism,  Fpjedrich  Albert  Lange 
(1828-1875).  Lange's  great  work  falls  into  two  divisions. 
Materialism  before  Kant,  and  modern  Materialism.  The 
first  is  divided  into  four  sections,  which  treat  respectively 
of  antiquity,  the  transition  period,  the  seventeenth  century, 
and  the  eighteenth  century.  In  the  first  of  these  Lange 
explains  how  the  earliest  philosopical  attempts  necessarily 
led  to  a  materialism,  of  which  the  highest  development 
was  in  the  theory  of  Demokritos,  who  undoubtedly  gave 
expression  to  some  of  the  most  important  doctrines  of 
modern  science.  The  complementary  antithesis  to  materi- 
alism in  antiquity  Lange  finds  in  the  sceptical  sensualism 
of  Protagoras.  These  are  alike  opposed  to  the  Sokratic- 
Platonic  philosophy.  This  portion  of  the  work  contains 
much  valuable  and  interesting  criticism.  The  second 
section,  which  deals,  beside,  with  the  attitude  of  the  three 
monotheistic  religions  to  Materialism,  shows  the  essentially 
antipathetic  nature  of  the  Aristotelian  philosophy,  to  the 
pure  empiricism  of  natural  science,  which  latter  indeed 
only  became  possible,  on  the  fall  of  Aristotelianism  from 
the  supremacy  it  held  during  the  middle  ages.  The  third 
section  treats  of  Gassendi  and  Ilobbes  as  the  fathers  of 
modern  Materialism,  and  of  their  influence  on  the  empiricist 


LANGE.  363 

movement  in  England ;  also  of  the  devleopment  of  the 
Cartesian  mechanical  theory  of  the  universe  on  the  conti- 
nent, into  the  thorough-going  Materialism  of  La  Mettrie 
and  his  successors.  This  last  is  dealt  with  in  the  fourth 
section  of  the  first  book,  which  also  contains  Lange's  state- 
ment of  his  own  position  towards  Materialism.  While 
acknowledging  the  materialistic  attitude  to  be  the  only- 
one  comj^atible  with  the  true  scientific  view  of  the  universe, 
he  finds  its  weak  point  in  the  non-recognition  of  the  fact 
that  the  scientific  as2:)ect  of  things  is  not  the  only  one,  but 
that  there  are  other  ways  of  envisaging  the  universe  which 
if  ignored  make  man  one-sided. 

The  second  book  treating  of  the  history  of  Materialism 
since  Kant,  is  also  arranged  in  four  sections,  the  first  deal- 
ing with  Kant  himself  and  his  relation  to  Materialism, 
together  with  the  post-Kantian  materialists,  Feuerbach, 
Moleschott,  Buchner,  Czolbe,  &c.,  in  the  course  of  which 
Lange  clearly  shows  Kant  to  be  the  dividing  line  which 
has  cut  off  the  possibility  of  any  return  to  the  old  naive 
Materialism  of  the  last  century.  The  second  section  is 
concerned  more  particularly  Avith  the  questions  raised  by 
recent  scientific  research.  The  result  arrived  at  is  that 
while  we  have  to  thank  Materialism  for  the  banishment 
of  the  notions  of  miracle  and  arbitrariness  from  nature, 
and  for  its  deliverance  of  men  from  the  fear  of  super- 
natural powers  and  agencies ;  that  notwithstanding,  its 
central  positive  dogma  of  the  absoluteness  of  corporeal 
substance  cannot  stand  in  face  of  the  advances  of  modern 
thought  alike  in  physic  and  metaphysic.  The  law  of  the 
persistence  of  force  is  altogether  incompatible  with  the 
dogmatic  side  of  materialism.  Johannes  Mliller's  researches 
into  the  physiology  of  the  senses  bring  us  back  from  a 
standpoint  of  physical  science  to  the  essentially  meta- 
physical result,  that  the  sense-world,  our  own  body  of 
course  included,  is  only  a  product  of  our  sense-organisa- 
tion. The  latter  portion  of  the  work  contains  an  able 
criticism  of  the  current  political  economy.  Lange  strongly 
deprecates  the  tendency  to  confound  truth  in  the  sense  of 
mere  theoretical  truth  with  worth  or  desirability.  Man 
has  not  only  the  impulse  to  attain  to  truth,  but  also  to 
the  good  in  the  sense  of  the   worthful  in-itself.     Kant's 


364  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY. 

Ideas   are   an   instance   of  confusion   between  tliese  two 
essentially  disparate  things. 

Our  notice  of  Lange's  book,  one  wliicli  is  perhaps  more 
widely  read  than  any  other  philosophical  work  in  Germany 
at  the  present  time,  and  which  has  been  translated  into 
most  European  languages,  aptly  closes  our  brief  sketch  of 
current  German  philosophical  literature,  since  the  philo- 
sophical activity  of  Germany  at  the  present  time  signalises 
itself  rather  in  the  department  of  historical  research  than 
in  that  of  constructive  thought.  The  names  of  Kuno 
Fischer,  of  Erdmann,  of  Urberweg,  of  Zeller,  and  many 
more,  now  living  or  but  recently  dead,  that  is  well-nigh  all 
the  most  important  German  philosophical  writers  of  the 
present  day,  illustrate  this  remark.  This  tendency  of 
German  philosophical  thought  to  turn  for  its  aliment  to 
historical  studies  is  by  no  means  an  unmixed  evil,  if  an 
evil  at  all.  The  time  has  passed,  if  indeed  it  ever  was, 
when  independent  thought  was  of  itself  almost  sufficient 
for  serious  and  lasting  philosophical  work.  Henceforward 
every  new  departure  or  development  in  philosophy  must 
not  merely  take  casual  account  of,  but  be  consciously  based 
on,  the  general  evolution  of  philosophy  in  the  past.  He 
who  aspires  to  be  a  serious  thinker  and  neglects  the 
history  of  philosophy  seals  the  fate  of  his  work.  For  this 
reason  the  research  of  the  Germans  into  the  history  of 
philosophy  is  a  necessary  element  in  the  future  progress  of 
philosophy.  We  now  leave  Germany  to  consider  the 
recent  and  current  movement  of  philosophy  in  France  and 
England. 

The  French  as  a  nation  have  never  been  remarkable  for 
originality  in  speculative  thought,  setting  aside  one  or  two 
noteworthy  exceptions,  of  which  Descartes  is  the  most 
striking.  As  a  result,  there  is  only  one  modern  French 
thinker  who  will  fall  within  the  scope  of  the  present  work, 
and  he  not  so  much  because  of  his  originality  as  on 
account  of  his  relations  to  contemporary  English  thought 
and  of  the  influence  he  has  exercised  directly  or  indirectly 
on  the  average  "cultured"  Englishman  of  the  present 
generation.  The  thinker  referred  to  is  Auguste  Comte. 
Comte  was  born  at  Montpellier  in  1798,  and  died  at  Paris 


COMTE.  365 

in  1857.  Originally  a  disciple  of  Saint-Simon,  the  most 
learned  and  original  of  the  Utopian-Socialist  thinkers  of 
the  first  half  of  the  present  century,  Comte's  joolitical 
and  social  speculations  hear  the  unmistakable  impress  of 
their  original,  though  it  may  be  fairly  doubted  whether 
this  has  been  improved  by  the  transformation  it  has 
undergone.  The  philosophical  side  of  "  Positivism,"  as 
Comte  designated  his  system,  consists  in  a  classification  of 
the  mathematical  and  natural  sciences  and  a  systemati- 
sation  of  the  conclusions  of  scientific  method.  The  net 
result  is  not  altogether  unlike  the  system  of  Hegel  in- 
verted. The  great  polemic  of  the  Philosophie  Positive  is 
against  what  Comte  terms  the  metaphysical  spirit  and 
metaj^hj^sical  entities,  but  which,  translated  into  other 
language,  are  simply  the  hypostasized  abstractions  proper 
to  the  absiract-dogmatic  phase  of  thought.  This  is  all 
that  is  meant  by  the  second  of  the  three  stages  through 
which  Auguste  Comte  claims  the  human  mind  to  pass. 

The  parallel  between  Comte  and  Hegel,  just  referred  to, 
has  been  noticed  elsewhere.  "  It  is  worthy  of  remark," 
says  Mr.  Shadworth-Hodgson  ('  Time  and  Space,'  p.  399 
et  seq.),  "  that  there  are  many  points  of  resemblance 
between  the  Logic  of  Hegel,  the  protagonist  of  Ontology, 
and  the  Philosojyhie  Positive  of  Comte,  the  protagonist  of 
Positivism.  There  is  first  the  similarity  of  Hegel's 
Absolute  Mind  and  Comte's  Vrai  Grand  Eire,  or  Humanity, 
each  of  which  is  the  concomitant  result,  if  I  may  so  speak, 
of  the  evolution  of  the  world-history;  each  of  which  is 
personified  as  a  single  individual ;  and  each  of  which  is 
the  object  of  divine  honours;  and  these  three  points  of 
similarity  suppose  several  minor  ones.  Then  again,  there 
is  the  progression  by  triplets  in  Hegel,  in  which  the  first 
member  is  the  an  sich,  the  last  the  an  unci  fiir  sich,  and  the 
middle  the  transition  between  them  ;  while  the  last  stage, 
when  reached,  throws  back  light  upon  the  nature  of  both 
the  previous  stages,  not  understood  before  they  had  pro- 
duced their  results.  To  this  answers  Comte's  doctrine  of 
a  triple  stage  in  the  actual  history  of  all  development,  the 
middle  of  which  is  but  a  transitional  state,  which  cannot 
be  judged  of  till  the  last  stage  has  been  reached,  for  which 
it  was  a   preparation ;  for  instance,  in   the  fields  of  the 


866  MODERiq    PHILOSOPHY. 

intellectual,  the  active,  and  the  affective  functions  of  man, 
three  stages  may  be  observed :  in  the  first,  the  fictive,  the 
abstract,  and  the  positive  stage  ;  in  the  second,  the  con- 
quering, the  defensive,  and  the  industrial ;  and  in  the 
third,  the  domestic,  the  civil,  and  the  universal."  Poli- 
tique Positive,  vol.  4,  chap.  iii.  p.  177.  And  again  ('Time 
and  Space,'  pp.  401-2),  Mr.  Shadworth-Hodgson  continues  : 
"  Both  writers,  each  from  his  own  point  of  view,  and  in 
his  own  half  of  the  world,  move  round  the  same  centre ; 
for  the  principle  which  they  share  is  the  central  truth  of 
their  two  systems.  This  truth  in  Hegel  is,  that  the 
universe  can  only  be  described,  analysed,  and  known 
within  itself.  In  the  Philosophie  Positive,  the  ruling 
thought,  as  exhibited  in  the  Law  of  the  Three  States  and 
elsewhere,  is,  that  the  search  after  causes  is  vain,  and  is 
superseded  by  the  search  after  laws.  In  other  words, 
analyse  the  order  of  co-existence  and  the  order  of  sequence 
of  phenomena  within  the  world  of  phenomena,  but  seek 
no  cause  for  any  of  them  that  is  not  itself  a  phenomenon. 
Both  conceptions  are  the  same,  namely,  to  keep  within 
phenomena,  to  analyse  their  order  and  interdependence, 
and  to  abstain  from  going  beyond  or  seeking  the  Why  of 
the  universe;  instead  of  this,  to  seek  only  for  the 
necessary  or  universal  antecedents  of  particular  objects,  as 
parts  of  the  whole.  A  difference  between  them  there  is, 
and  a  wide  one,  namely,  that  this  mode  of  philosophising 
is  in  Comte  a  renunciation  of  an  attempt  as  useless,  while 
in  Hegel  it  is  a  claim  to  have  succeeded  in  that  attempt, 
the  attempt  to  seize  the  Absolute.  Look  only  for  laws 
and  not  for  causes,  say  they  both  ;  philosophy  is  the  dis- 
covery of  laws  and  not  of  causes  ;  the  absolute  is  not  to  be 
seized,  remain  within  your  fixed  limits.  But  ^Nh.J  is  the 
absolute  not  to  be  seized?  With  Hegel  because  it  has 
been  seized  already,  is  defined,  and  contains  all  causes 
within  it ;  with  Comte,  because  it  cannot  be  seized  at  all, 
and  we  must  content  ourselves  without  causes.  Equally 
however  in  both  cases  is  the  search  for  cause  given  up."* 


*  While  quoting  tlie  above  passages  as  expressing  an  undoubted 
parallel  between  the  two  thinkers  in  question,  the  present  writer  must 
not  be  understood  as  accepting  every  statement  contained  in  them. 


COMTE.  •  oC7 

To  this  may  be  added  that  even  Conite's  polemic  against 
what  he  calls  materialism,  that  is  the  explanation  of  the 
phenomena  of  a  higher  plane  of  natnre  by  those  of  a 
lower,  e.g.  the  treatment  of  social  phenomena  on  physio- 
logical principles  alone,  or  of  vital  phenomena  on  chemical 
principles,  and  so  on,  has  its  parallel  in  the  potences  of 
Schelling  and  the  determinate  momenta  of  the  Natur- 
philosophie  of  Hegel. 

Comte's  law  of  the  three  stages  with  which  the  Positive 
Philosophy  opens  is  as  follows  :  "  That  each  of  our  leading 
conceptions — each  branch  of  our  knowledge — passes 
successively  through  three  different  theoretical  conditions  : 
the  Theological,  or  fictitious  ;  the  Metaphysical,  or 
abstract ;  and  the  Scientific,  or  positive.  In  other  words, 
the  human  mind,  by  its  nature,  employs  in  its  progress 
three  methods  of  philosophising,  the  character  of  which  is 
essentially  different,  and  even  radically  opposed,  viz.  the 
theological,  the  metaphysical,  and  the  positive  method. 
Hence  arise  three  philosophies,  or  general  systems  of  concep- 
tions on  the  aggregate  of  phenomena,  each  of  which  excludes 
the  others.  The  first  is  the  necessary  point  of  departure  of 
the  human  understanding ;  and  the  third  is  its  fixed  and 
definite  state.  The  second  is  merely  a  state  of  transition  " 
CComte's  '  Positive  Philosophy,'  Martineau,  vol.  i.  pp.  1-2). 
The  employment  of  the  word  metaphysical  to  denote  the 
second  of  these  stages  is  entirely  arbitrary.  The  originality 
and  importance  of  the  doctrine  itself  has  moreover  been 
greatly  exaggerated.  Students  of  Hegel  will  be  familiar 
with  the  truth  embodied  in  the  conception,  although 
otherwise  expressed.  In  the  first  of  the  three  stages,  the 
modifications  of  phenomena  are  referred  to  the  arbitrary 
wall  of  a  being  or  beings  believed  to  be  present  in  or 
ruling  over  those  phenomena ;  in  the  second  of  the  three 
stages,  the  cause  of  the  phenomena  and  their  modifications 
is  referred  to  certain  properties  inherent  in  bodies,  but 
which  are  abstracted  from  the  body  or  whole  to  which  they 
belong,  and  conceived  as  distiuct  entities  or  powers  acting 
upon  that  body  independently.  The  third,  the  so-called 
positive  or  scientific  stage,  abandons  the  search  for  causes 
which  had  characterised  the  two  previous  stages,  and 
restricts  itself  to  the  endeavour  to  discover  the  law,  that 


368  MODEEN    PHILOSOPHY. 

is  the  order  of  succession  and  co-existence  obtaining 
within  the  various  groups  or  departments  of  natural 
phenomena. 

According  to  Auguste  Comte,  all  sciences  have  reached 
the  positive  stage,  to  a  greater  or  less  extent  according  to 
the  complexity  or  simplicity  of  their  subject-matter,  with 
the  exception  of  the  last  and  most  complex  of  them  all,  the 
science  of  man  considered  as  a  social  and  a  moral  being. 
Of  this  last  science,  as  a  science,  he  claims  to  have  been  the 
founder,  and  to  it  he  gives  the  name  of  Sociology.  Comte 
had  inherited  from  Saint-Simon  the  idea  that  all  mere 
theoretical  knowledge,  and  indeed  all  special  departments 
of  human  activity  whatever,  should  be  subordinate  to  one 
great  practical  end ;  the  reorgani>sation  o£  human  life  and 
society.  This  it  is  only  fair  to  remember  was  the  goal  he 
set  before  him  from  the  first,  and  to  this  goal,  there  can  be 
no  doubt,  he  meant  all  his  scientific  work  to  lead.  Hence 
the  filiation  of  the  sciences  in  the  form  of  a  hierarchy 
culminating  in  Sociology,  and  hence  the  importance 
attached  to  the  elaboration  of  the  latter  science.  The 
positive  method  hitherto  had  been  confined  in  its  appli- 
cation to  special  groups  or  orders  of  phenomena,  in  other 
words,  the  separate  sciences,  without  those  sciences  ever 
having  been  co-ordinated  into  a  whole  or  complete  philo- 
sophy in  accordance  with  that  method.  This  co-ordination 
it  is  the  aim  of  the  Positive  Philosophy  to  accomplish. 
The  key  to  the  arrangement  of  the  sciences  Comte  finds 
in  the  notions,  (1)  that  the  order  of  scientific  study 
follows  the  order  of  phenomena:  and  (2)  that  the  more 
special  and  complex  phenomena  depend  upon  the  more 
general  and  simple.  The  most  general  facts  will  therefore 
be  the  first  that  will  be  studied,  and  the  first  to  reach 
perfection  as  regards  their  formulation,  i.e.  the  positive 
method.  The  hierarchy  followiug  these  principles  is  ar- 
ranged thus :  Mathematics,  Astronomy,  Physics,  Chemistry, 
Biology,  and  Sociology;  each  step  in  this  arrangement 
involves  something  specially  its  ovra  over  and  above  that 
involved  in  the  previous  step.  It  should  be  premised 
that  Comte  makes  a  primary  distinction  between  abstract 
and  concrete  sciences  ;  the  first  (science  proper)  with  which 
the  hierarchy  is   alone  concerned,  treats  of  the  abstract 


COMTE.  369 

relations  or  general  laws  of  the  various  groups  of  pheno- 
mena, the  second  with  the  history  or  description  of  the  phe- 
nomena themselves,  and  with  the  special  application  of 
those  laws. 

The  Philosopliie  Positive  is  comprised  in  six  volumes,  of 
which  the  first  three  treat  of  the  simpler  or  inferior 
sciences,  and  the  last  three  of  Sociology,  which,  as  we  have 
said,  it  is  the  great  aim  of  Angnste  Comte  to  establish  on 
a  positive,  that  is,  inductive,  basis.  The  law  of  the  three 
states  and  the  conception  of  the  hierarchy  of  the  sciences 
together  constitute  the  framework  of  the  Comtian  system. 
The  one  shows  us  the  necessary  course  of  human  know- 
ledge ;  the  other  the  necessary  dependecce  of  phenomena, 
and  brings  the  phenomena  of  human  society  as  much 
under  the  domain  of  law  as  those  of  Chemistrj^  or  Physics. 
This  does  not  mean  with  Comte,  that  social  phenomena 
can  be  adequately  treated  on  the  methods  of  any  of  the 
lower  sciences  ;  on  the  contrary,  he  especially  insists  on 
each  science  having  its  own  special  logic,  terming  the  non- 
recognition  of  this  fact — the  treatment  of  a  higher  science 
on  the  methods  of  a  lower — materialism ;  all  he  means  is 
that  social  science  is  impossible  a|3art  from  Biology,  that 
this  again  presupposes  Chemistry,  while  Chemistry  pre- 
supposes Physics,  &c. ;  the  whole  series  of  the  sciences 
resting  on  the  fundamental  laws  of  number,  proportion, 
magnitude,  &c.,  that  is,  on  Mathematics. 

Having  given  a  brief  view  of  the  general  principles  on 
which  Positivism  rests,  we  projoose  to  say  a  few  words, 
first  on  Comte's  view  of  historic  evolution  and  afterwards 
on  the  scheme  of  social  reconstruction,  in  the  elaboration 
i.if  which  the  later  period  of  his  career  was  occupied. 
The  fundamental  idea  of  Comte's  philosophy  of  history 
is  the  coincidence  of  the  first  or  theological  stage  of  the 
nnman  mind  with  a  military  state  of  society.     This,  on 

-sing  into  Avhat  Comte  terms  the  metaphysical  stage,  is 

■ompanied  by  a  conflict  between  the  military  and  the 
industrial  spirit,  which  last  is  the  social  expression  of  the 
rial  stage,  the  positive  or  scientific.  Briefly  expressed, 
the  division  is  into  offensive  militaiyism,  defensive 
aiilitaryism,  and  industry.  The  key  to  Comte's  theory  of 
history  is  thus  to  be  found  in  his  law  of  the  three  stages, 

2  B 


370  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY. 

from  which  it  is  further  obvious  that  he  regards  the  cardinal 
factor  in  human  development  (a  point  in  which  the  re- 
doubtable founder  of  Positivism  is  in  full  accord  with  the 
much  decried  "  metaphysical  "  thinkers  of  the  eighteenth 
century)  to  be  man's  intellectual  side. 

"  Though  the  elements  of  our  social  evolution  are 
connected  and  always  acting  on  each  other,  one  must  be 
preponderant,  in  order  to  give  an  impulse  to  the  rest, 
though  they  may,  in  their  turn,  so  act  upon  it  as  to  cause 
its  further  expansion.  AVe  must  find  out  this  superior 
element,  leaving  the  lower  degrees  of  subordination  to 
disclose  themselves  as  we  proceed ;  and  we  have  not  to 
search  far  for  this  element,  as  we  cannot  err  in  taking  that 
which  can  be  best  conceived  of  apart  from  the  rest,  not- 
withstanding their  necessary  connection,  while  the  con- 
sideration of  it  would  enter  into  the  study  of  the  others. 
This  double  characteristic  points  out  the  intellectual  evo- 
lution as  the  prejDonderant  principle.  If  the  intellectual 
point  of  ^dew  was  the  chief  in  our  statical  study  of  the 
organism,  much  more  must  it  be  so  in  the  dynamical  case. 
If  our  reason  required  at  the  outset  the  awakening  and 
stimulating  influence  of  the  appetites,  the  passions,  and 
the  sentiments,  not  the  less  has  human  progression  gone 
forward  under  its  direction.  It  is  only  through  the  more 
and  more  marked  influence  of  the  reason  over  the  general 
conduct  of  Man  and  of  society,  that  the  gradual  march  of  our 
race  has  attained  that  regularity  and  persevering  continuity 
which  distinguish  it  so  radically  from  the  desultory  and 
barren  expansion  of  even  the  highest  of  the  animal  orders, 
which  share,  and  with  enhanced  strength,  the  ajjpetites, 
the  passions,  and  even  the  primary  sentiments  of  Man  " 
(Comte's  '  Positive  Philosophy,'  Martineau,  vol.  ii.  p.  156). 

After  stating  the  principles  of  the  new  science,  Comte 
proceeds  to  give  a  sketch  of  historic  evolution  in  the  light 
of  these  principles.  The  theological  and  military  system 
already  begins  with  the  primitive  stage  of  universal 
fetichism  in  which  every  object  is  personified  or  endowed 
with  will.  Its  immediate  development  is  the  ascendency 
of  star-worship  (astrolatry)  merging  into  polytheism,  the 
most  perfect  type  of  which  is  to  be  found  in  the  theocratio 
civilisations  of  the  East,  which  represent  its  first  phase, 


COMTE.  371 

and  of  which  the  ancient  Egyptian  civilisation  may  be 
taken  as  a  model.  In  the  second  phase  presented  in  the 
earlier  classical  civilisation  of  Greece,  we  have  what  Comte 
terms  an  intellectual  polytheism.  No  priestly  caste  exists 
snch  as  in  Egjq^t.  As  a  consequence,  intellectual  activity 
has  a  free  outlet.  In  the  third  or  Eoman  period,  that  of 
the  later  classical  polytheism,  we  have  a  civilisation  in 
which  military  ism  is  supreme,  and  conquest  the  all-power- 
ful motive-power,  nnd  not  as  in  Greece  a  mere  co-ordinate 
factor  in  social  lilo,  or  as  in  Egjq^t  subordinate  to  a 
sacerdotal  class.  The  old  polytheism  already  undermined 
by  the  metajDhysical  thought  of  Greece,  could  now  no 
longer  offer  any  resistance  to  the  incursion  of  Semitic 
monotheism.  The  prevailing  conception  itself  even  had 
come  to  assume  in  the  popular  mind  a  form  somewhat 
analogous  to  this.  "The  popular  idea  of  monotheism," 
says  Comte,  "  closely  resembles  the  latest  polytheistic  con- 
ception of  a  multitude  of  supernatural  beings,  subjected 
directly,  regularly,  and  permanently  to  the  sway  of  a 
single  will,  by  which  their  respective  offices  are  appointed; 
and  the  popular  instinct  justly  rejects  as  barren  the  notion 
of  a  god  destitute  of  ministers.  Thus  regarded,  the  transi- 
tion, through  the  idea  of  Fate,  to  the  conception  of  Provi- 
dence, is  clear  enough,  as  effected  by  the  metaphysical 
spirit  in  its  growth." 

The  civilisation  in  which  the  new  monotheism  issued 
was  the  feudal-catholic  organisation  of  the  middle  ages. 
This,  the  ideal  period  of  Positivism,  is  characterised  first 
and  foremost  by  the  separation  of  the  spiritual  and 
temporal  powers,  which  is  accompanied  by  the  conversion 
of  slavery  into  serfdom,  by  the  institution  of  chivalry,  by 
the  domination  of  morality  over  polity,  &c.  With  the 
decline  and  break-up  of  mediaeval  society  commences  the 
transitional  era  of  the  "  metaphysical  sj)irit  "  par  excellence^ 
which  reaches  its  culmination  in  the  revolutionary  philo- 
sophy of  the  eighteenth  century,  and  in  the  ideas,  such  as 
"  natural  religion,"  "popular  sovereignty,"  "  liberty,"  &c., 
characteristic  of  the  revolutionary  epoch  of  which  the 
great  crisis  was  the  French  Eevolution,  but  through  which 
we  are  still  passing.  This  is  destined  in  its  turn  to  issue 
in  the  positive  regime^  social,  political,  and  religious,  as 

2  B  2 


oi2  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY 

described  in  Comte's  work,  *  The  Positive  Polity,'  and  in  a 
condensed  form  in  the  '  Positivist  Catechism,'  and  the 
'  General  View  of  Positivism.'  This,  as  the  reader  is 
doubtless  aware,  has  been  described  as  Catholicism  minus 
Christianity ;  with  how  much  of  justice  may  be  gathered 
from  what  follows. 

Comte's  aim  in  the  constructive  portion  of  his  work  was 
to  reconstitute  human  life  "  without  God  or  King  "  *  (sans 
Dieu  ni  Roi).  It  has  been  alleged  by  a  certain  section  of 
Comte's  disciples  that  there  is  a  diiference  of  attitude, 
amounting,  indeed,  to  a  change  of  front,  between  the 
earlier  and  the  later  sides  of  Comte's  doctrine.  An 
examination  of  the  works  themselves  will,  we  think, 
convince  the  candid  outsider  that  there  is  no  adequate 
ground  for  this  assertion.  In  the  later  works,  it  is  true,  the 
less  pleasing  sides  of  Comte's  temper  and  character  assume 
greater  prominence  than  in  the  earlier.  Views  which  in 
the  Philosophie  Positive  are  expressed  with  the  modesty  and 
reserve  of  the  philosopher,  reappear  in  the  Politique  Positive 
and  other  writings,  belonging  to  this  period,  with  all  the 
asperity  of  dogmas  pronounced  ex  cathedra  by  a  pontiff,  and 
to  dispute  which  is  impious.  Comte's  religious  disciples 
would  probably  defend  this  attitude  as  becoming  the 
prophet-priest  of  a  new  cultus ;  but  that  of  course  is 
their  affair.  It  must  also  be  remembered  that  the  hypo- 
thetical construction  of  a  social  order  must  necessarily 
involve  a  play  of  the  imagination  which  would  be 
altogether  out  of  place  in  what  claims  to  be  a  scientific 
exposition. 

Comte  divides  this  portion  of  his  system  into  the 
"  worship,"  the  "  doctrine,"  and  the  "  regime,^'  or  "  mode 
of  life."  The  worship  has  for  its  object  Humanity 
considered  as  a  corporate  being,  past,  present,  and  to 
come.  For  this  worship,  public  and  private,  an  elaborate 
ceremonial  is  mapped  out,  rivalling  the  Catholic  ritual. 
The  priesthood  of  the  Comtian  cultus  are  to  be  entrusted 
with   the  functions   of  teaching  and   moral  exhortation. 

*  Not  as  Mr.  Bridges  reudefs  it  on  the  titlepage  of  his  translation 
of  the  '  General  View  of  Positivism '  (presumably  with  a  wholesome 
dread  of  tlie  British  Philistine  before  his  eyes)  irrespectively  of  God  or 

Kin":. 


COMTE.  oY.J 

They  are  to  constitute  a  great  spiritual  power,  resembling 
the  Catholic  hierarchy  of  the  middle  ages,  but  posses- 
sing neither  wealth  nor  material  influence.  The  doctrine 
tiiught,  the  creed  of  the  new  religion,  consists  of  course 
of  the  Positive  Philosophy.  The  third  part,  "the  life," 
embraces  a  description  of  the  Comtian  social  and  political 
organization  which  is  to  be  the  material  basis  of  the 
whole.  Politically  the  Positivist  world  is  to  consist  of  a 
commonwealth,  at  first  composed  of  the  five  western  nations 
of  Europe,  though  ultimately  destined  to  absorb  the  whole 
world.  Socially,  the  modern  distinction  of  classes  with 
some  modification  is  to  be  maintained.  The  middle  classes 
are  to  form  a  hierarchy  on  an  ascending  scale,  proceeding 
from  the  agricultural  interest,  which  is  the  lowest,  to  the 
manufacturing  interest,  thence  to  the  mercantile  interest, 
and  culminating  in  the  banking  interest.  Outside  this 
hierarchy  is  the  bulk  of  the  peo^Dle,  the  proletariat  together 
with  the  women  who  are  to  be  rigorously  excluded  from  all 
industrial  as  well  as  public  function,  and  of  course  the 
priestly  class.  The  various  minute,  and  to  the  non- 
PositiAdst,  exceedingly  funny  regulations  of  public  and 
private  conduct,  may  be  perused  in  the  works  above 
mentioned. 

As  regards  the  philosophical  side  of  Positivism,  it  may 
be  and  has  been  criticised  from  a  variety  of  standpoints. 
The  most  important  ad  liominem  criticism  is  that  of  the 
scientific  specialist  who  declares  Comte's  treatment  of  the 
special  sciences  in  the  first  three  volumes  of  the  Philosojjhie 
Positive  to  display  inadequate  knowledge  of  the  several 
subjects  treated,  and  a  dogmatism  as  to  results,  which  was 
not  justified  by  the  then  state  of  those  sciences,  as  is 
proved  by  the  fact  that  many  of  them  have  failed  to  stand 
the  test  of  later  research.  The  hierarchy  itself,  as  laid 
down  by  Comte,  has  been  severely  challenged  in  various 
quarters,  and  the  artificial  character  of  any  purely  linear 
arrangement  has  been  more  than  once  pointed  out. 

Turning  to  what  many  of  his  disciples  think  Comte's 
greatest  title  to  philosophic  fame,  the  foundation  and 
elaboration  of  the  science  of  Sociology,  we  should  begin  by 
denying  his  claim  to  originality.  Kant  clearly  had  the 
conception  of  such  a  science,  as  already  mentioned  (see 


374  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY. 

above,  p.  251);  tlie  same  may  be  said  of  Herder ;  while 
Hegel  distinctly  formulated  a  sociological  doctrine,  besides 
working  out  a  philosophy  of  history  on  its  lines.  The 
notion,  therefore,  of  a  continuity  between  the  order  of 
nature  and  that  of  human  society  was  certainly  not  new. 
Just  as  little  original  was  the  notion  of  the  main  deter- 
minant of  human  progress  being  the  speculative  side  of 
things;  this  was  the  view  of  the  French  eighteenth- 
century  thinker,  of  a  Turgot  and  Condorcet,  no  less  than 
of  the  German  metaphysician.  That  there  are  true  and 
valuable  suggestions  to  be  found  in  Comte's  philosophy 
of  history,  it  would  be  unjust  to  deny ;  but  it  Avould  be 
vain  to  deny  that  alike  its  fundamental  principle  and 
much  of  its  working-out  belongs  to  an  antiquated  method 
of  dealing  with  history,  and  will  not  stand  in  face  of  the 
light  thrown  upon  social  development  by  later  thought, 
in  which,  for  the  first  time,  we  have  the  clue  to  a  really 
scientific  theory  of  historical  development — a  theory  which 
finds  the  determining  factor  in  progress,  to  lie  in  economical 
and  social  condition  rather  than  in  speculative  thought — 
in  short,  which  treats  political,  religious  and  social  forms 
as  primarily  growing  out  of  material  conditions,  and  not 
vice-versa,  as  in  all  preceding  philosophies  of  history. 

Having  said  thus  much  in  derogation  of  the  exaggerated 
claims  to  recognition  sometimes  made  on  behalf  of  Comt^ 
as  regards  Sociology,  it  remains  to  notice  the  real  step  he 
undoubtedly  effected ;  this  consisted  in  emphasising  the 
truth  that  the  highest  significance  of  the  individual  is  to 
be  found  in  Society  and  a  fortiori  in  Humanity.  No  one 
before  so  distinctly  seized  the  fact  of  the  essential  unreality 
of  the  individual  considered  per  se — the  fact  that  his  end 
is  social.  The  travesty  of  this  doctrine  furnished  in  the 
religious  cultiis  of  Positivism  must  not  blind  us  to  its 
intrinsic  importance. 

There  is  one  claim  made  by  the  Positivists  on  behalf  of 
their  master,  which  we  think  every  non-Comtian  ac- 
quainted with  the  information  we  possess  as  to  his 
character  will  be  inclined  to  meet  with  an  unqualified 
denial.  We  are  asked  to  admire,  and  indeed  to  regard  as 
in  eifect  a  paragon  of  moral  excellence,  the  personality 
of  Comte  himself  as  exhibited  in  his  life.     Now  we  do  not 


COMTE.  o75 

hesitate  to  say  that  to  most  persons  who  have  read  Littre's 
biography  of  Comte,  and  are  tolerably  familiar  with  the 
later  works,  Comte's  personality  will  appear  as  an  exceed- 
ingly repulsive  one,  judged  by  all  ordinary  standards. 
Possessed  of  a  personal  vanity  so  oifensive  in  its  manifesta- 
tions and  grotesque  in  its  proportions,  as  to  make  us  almost 
pardon  it  on  the  ground  of  disease,  a  superficial  reader  might 
be  excused  for  supposing  that  the  one  object  of  the  founder 
of  Positivism  was  its  satisfaction.  This  of  course  would 
be  an  unfair  judgment,  but  the  fact  remains  that  before  this 
vanity  no  relation  in  life  was  sacred.  After  having  absorbed 
the  thought  of  a  man  of  far  greater  genius,  if  of  less  learning 
and  capacity  for  hard  work  than  himself;  a  man  who  had 
befriended  him  in  his  youth,  when  he  most  needed  friend- 
ship, he  not  only  found  no  difficulty  in  casting  him  aside, 
when  he  saw  the  way  clear  for  posing  as  an  independent 
thinker,  but  with  incredible  baseness  could  stoop  to  vilify 
his  former  friend,  lest  perchance  that  friend  should  carry 
off  a  scintilla  of  the  merit  there  was  in  his  own  works. 
A  somewhat  similar  occui-rence  took  place  with  regard  to 
John  Stuart  Mill,  on  whose  generosity  he  lived  for  a 
considerable  time.  When  Mill  found  it  impossible  to 
continue  the  assistance  he,  in  conjunction  with  Grote  and 
Molesworth,  had  been  affording,  all  the  recognition 
received  was  a  rebuke  savouring  of  the  worst  type  of 
pretentious  charlatanry.  These  may  be  old  charges, 
but  they  have  never  been  satisfactorily  refuted,  and 
the  opinion  one  unavoidably  forms  of  the  moral  dis- 
position they  indicate  is  confirmed  not  only  by  number- 
less other  small  traits  (even  if  we  exonerate  Comte  from 
all  blame  in  his  relations  to  his  wife),  but  by  the  tone  of 
many  passages  in  the  '  General  View,'  by  almost  every 
page  of  the  '  Catechism,'  and  by  much  in  the  '  Corre- 
spondence.' In  this  particular  instance  one  may  be 
excused  noting  these  things,  since  it  is  by  way  of  protest 
against  the  attempt  that  is  sometimes  made  to  convert  one 
of  the  most  morally  inferior  of  mortals,  into  something 
like  an  object  of  adoration. 

The  quite  theological  reverence  with  which  Positivists 
regard  the  scriptures  of  their  Messiah  is  well  known. 
Since   Auguste   Comte  wrote,  and  even  since  his  death, 


376  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY. 

advances  have  been  made  in  science,  which  to  a  great 
extent  have  revolutionised  conclusions  accepted  during  the 
earlier  half  of  the  century.  It  is  not  Comte's  fault  there- 
fore if  there  is  much  in  the  scientific  aspects  of  his  doctrine 
which  is  hopelessly  obsolete.  But  the  same  cannot  be  said 
of  certain  of  his  followers,  when  in  their  zeal  for  the  infalli- 
bility of  the  sacred  text  they  resent  advances  in  science 
and  even  denounce  those  whose  names  are  connected  with 
them.  After  this  it  can  only  excite  a  smile,  that  Comte 
having  been  gifted  with  a  particularly  bad  literary  style, 
it  should  be  the  mark  of  the  good  Positivist  to  underrate 
matters  of  style  in  general. 

Positivism,  we  may  remark  in  conclusion,  partakes  of  the 
nature  of  those  systems,  the  inevitable  product  of  great 
periods  of  transition,  which  are  imperfect  assimilations  of 
a  new  principle,  and  which  appear  as  hybrids  between 
the  existing  yet  decaying  order  of  things  and  ideas 
and  the  new  tendencies  which  are  beginning  to  destroy 
it,  manifesting  itself  of  course  in  its  main  strength  on 
the  particular  side  of  human  affairs  on  which  the  pro- 
gressive movement  primarily  turns.  During  the  period  of 
the  decline  of  the  Eoman  empire  the  most  prominent  aspect 
of  the  movement  of  change  was  Ethical  and  Speculative  ; 
its  expression  being  in  the  Christian  religion  as  opposed 
to  Paganism.  Hence  we  have  the  Semi- Pagan,  Semi- 
Christian,  Gnostic  systems  and  subsequently  that  of 
Manes,  all  of  which  combine  elements  belonging  both  to 
Christianity  and  Paganism.  The  dominant  aspect  of  the 
new  tendencies  in  our  present  period  of  transition  is  more 
fundamental ;  it  is,  that  is  to  say,  toward  a  material 
reconstrudion  of  society  on  a  basis  of  equality,  apart  from 
the  theological  and  ethical  sanctions  which  have  hitherto 
obtained.  Positivism  in  part  recognises  this;  its  main 
interest  lies  in  social  renovation,  but  in  this  it  seeks  to 
preserve  the  material  basis  of  the  present  society  while 
rejecting  its  speculative  counterpart.  Even  its  ethics  it 
retains.  The  change  is  to  be  efi'ected  on  the  old  principles 
of  individual  ethical  initiative  and  regeneratiou  from 
within,  rather  than  through  economic  and  social  recon- 
struction. Its  non-theological  attitude,  its  profes.-ed  devo- 
tion to  human  progress  as  the  supreme  end  of  all  institu- 


MILL.  o77 

tions,  ill  accords  with  the  superstitious  reverence  attached 
to  certain  traditional  social  forms.  The  immolation  of 
human  happiness  before  the  Comtian  Moloch  "  social 
order "  is  in  keeping  with  a  cultas  in  which  humaiiity  is 
transformed  into  a  supreme  fetich,  demanding  a  drastic 
asceticism  as  the  highest  expression  of  her  worship,  and 
of  which  the  prospective  virgin  mother  is  the  symbol  and 
ideal. 

The  contemporary  British  philosophical  movements  were 
until  the  advent  of  Herbert  Spencer  almost  exclusively 
confined  to  Psychology  and  formal  Logic.  In  the  past 
generation  the  main  i)hilosophical  controversey  was  that 
between  the  Empirical  Associationists  and  Psychological 
Intuitionists,  represented  on  the  one  side  by  the  younger 
Mill,  following  the  footsteps  of  his  father,  and  on  the  other, 
Sir  William  Hamilton,  in  conjunction  with  whom  may  be 
mentioned  his  i)upil,  Henry  Longueville  Mansel.  The 
results  of  Aesociationism  and  of  the  Scotch  school  of  Psy- 
chology, generally,  have  been  s^^stematized  and  presented 
a  form  adapted  to  university  students  by  Alexander  Bain. 

The  philosophy  of  Mill,  and  the  modern  empirical 
school,  generally,  is  really  but  little  more  than  a  restate- 
ment of  the  principles  laid  down  in  the  seventeenth  and 
eighteenth  centuries  by  Hobbes,  Locke,  Berkeley  and  Hume. 
The  reduction  of  all  mental  phenomena  to  the  em2:)irical 
association  of  ideas  is  its  characteristic.  The  intuitional 
school,  of  which  Hamilton  may  be  regarded  as  the  chief 
exponent,  was  a  development  with  modifications  along 
the  lines  of  Reid.  Both  schools  alike  reject  the  ten- 
dencies of  German  speculation,  which  at  this  period  was 
represented  in  this  island  by  one  writer  only,  namely 
Terrier,  the  author  of  the  '  Institutes  of  Metaphysic,'  who, 
although  an  original  writer,  had  but  imperfectly  assimi- 
lated its  results. 

Probably  no  one,  with  the  exception  perhaps  of  Herbert 
Spencer,  is  more  connected  with  philosophical  studies  in 
the  mind  of  the  average  Englishman  than  John  Stuart 
Mill.  During  the  latter  ]3art  of  his  life  he  was  eminently 
the  English  philosopher.  He  undoubtedly  contributed  to 
popularise   the  results  of  the  associational  school  to  an 


378  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY. 

extent  whicli  no  one  had  done  before  him.  The  lucidity 
of  his  style  was  sufficient  to  place  the  problems  with 
which  he  dealt  before  the  minds  of  persons  altogether  un- 
used to  abstract  thought.  Nevertheless,  Mill  cannot  be 
said  to  have  contributed  any  new  development  even  to 
psychology,  much  less  to  philosophy  in  general.  His 
father,  James  Mill,  was  in  the  direct  line  of  the  Scotch 
Psychological  School,  in  which  the  younger  Mill  in  conse- 
quence received  a  thorough  training  from  his  earliest 
years.  As  a  young  man  Mill  met  with  the  works  of 
August  Comte,  and  acknowledges  having  received  a 
powerful  stimulus  from  them.  All  Mill's  work  is  essen- 
tially critical.  Nearly  all  his  independent  contributions 
to  Psychology  are  contained  in  his  '  Examination  of 
Hamilton.'  It  is  here  that  the  dissertation  on  perception 
is  to  be  found,  the  result  of  which  is  Mill's  well-known 
definition  of  the  objective-real  as  "  permanent  possibility 
of  sensation."  The  philosophical  polemic  of  Mill's  life  as 
expressed  in  his  two  great  works — the  '  System  of  Logic ' 
and  the  '  Examination  of  Sir  William  Hamilton's  Philo- 
sophy '  above  referred  to — is  with  the  somewhat  crude 
psychological  theory  of  innate  ideas  against  which  Locke 
had  protested.  The  diiference  is,  however,  that  whereas 
in  Locke's  time  nobody  had  ever  conceived  such  monstro- 
sities, nor  would  have  conceived  of  them  had  not  Locke 
found  it  convenient  to  set  up  the  theory  as  a  target  to 
attack ;  Locke  having  once  started  the  doctrine  as  the 
object  of  his  polemic,  a  school  of  intuitionists  naturally 
grew  up  who  made  it  their  business  to  champion  this  doc- 
trine. Hamilton  and  his  school  were  the  upholders  of 
this  rival  psj^chological  theory.  We  believe  thinking 
men  will  generally  agree  when  we  describe  the  main  result 
of  Mill's  work  as  that  of  a  powerful  stimulus.  He  stirred  up 
the  minds  of  many  to  the  consideration  of  problems  which 
had  previously  Jain  outside  their  range  of  mental  vision. 

Alexander  Bain  is  probably  the  best  knoAvn  and  most 
voluminous  of  contemporary  British  writers  of  the 
psychological  school.  His  '  Sensations  and  Intellect,' 
and  '  Emotions  and  Will,'  his  '  ]\lental  and  Moral  Science,' 
and  his  '  Logic,  are  more  or  less  familiar  to  every  student, 
and  any  analysis  of  them  will  therefore  be  unnecessary. 


LEWES.  379 

We  may,  however,  mention  as  the  chief  original  result 
arrived  at  by  Bain  his  elaborate  attempt  in  the  second 
volume  of  his  '  Logic '  to  identify  the  notion  of  the  "  per- 
sistence of  force  "  with  that  of  causality,  or  more  accurately, 
to  deduce  causality  from  the  "persistence  of  force." 

The  versatile  writer  and  critic  George  Henry  Lewes 
(1817-78),  although  in  his  earlier  years  he  maybe  con- 
sidered simj^ly  as  an  adherent  of  the  '  Philosoj)hic  Positive,' 
towards  the  close  of  his  life  elaborated  a  system  of  his 
own,  embodied  in  a  work  entitled  '  Problems  of  Life  and 
Mind,'  which  although  not  completed  in  detail  at  the  time 
of  his  death,  was  sufdciently  advanced  to  aiford  a  general 
view  of  its  leading  principles.  Lewes's  deviations  from 
*' Positive"  method  lie  rather  in  the  direction  of  extend- 
ing its  scope.  Problems  which  his  master  Comte,  and  he 
himself  previously,  would  have  declared  insoluble,  he  now 
claims  to  treat  according  to  the  principles  of  science. 
"While  the  first  rule  of  his  philosophy  is  :  "no  problem  to 
be  mooted  unless  it  be  presented  in  terms  of  experience, 
and  be  capable  of  empirical  investigation,"  he  refuses  to 
admit  that  problems  hitherto  regarded  as  essentially 
metaphysical,  such  as  matter,  force,  cause,  law,  soul,  &c., 
cannot  be  presented  in  those  terms,  and  solved  on  the 
methods  of  induction.  Lewes  even  retains  the  name 
Metaphysics  for  these  probleais,  inventing  the  term 
Metempirics  for  their  treatment  on  non-empirical  methods. 
Each  problem  has  what  Lewes  terms  an  "  unexplored 
remainder,"  that  is  to  say,  an  unknowable  element  which 
has  to  be  eliminated  before  the  problem  can  be  dealt  with 
on  the  Positive  method.  No  science  is  more  than  sym- 
bolical of  reality.  "  Its  most  absolute  conclusions,"  says 
Lewes,  "  are  formed  from  abstractions  expressing  modes  of 
existence  which  never  were  and  never  could  be  real ;  and 
are  very  often  at  variance  with  sensible  experience." 
Scieace  thus  represents  a  transformed  reality,  an  ideal 
world  of  its  own.  "  Science  is  in  no  way  a  plain  transcript 
of  Eealit}^,  in  no  respect  a  picture  of  the  External  Order, 
but  wholly  an  ideal  construction,  in  which  the  manifold 
relations  of  Reals  are  taken  up  and  assimilated  by  the 
mind  and  then  transformed  into  relatious  of  ideas,  so  that 
the  world  of  sense  is  changed  into  the  world  of  thought.^* 


880  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY. 

The  aim  of  philosophy  is  not,  therefore,  to  give  a  magnified 
picture  of  the  workl,  as  it  might  appear  to  enhanced 
powers  of  sense,  but  to  reconstruct  an  ideal  world  of 
abstract  relations.  The  difference  between  the  recon- 
structed ideal  world  of  science  and  that  of  the  Metaphy- 
sicians, or  Metempiricists,  as  Lewes  would  call  them,  is, 
therefore,  that  the  one  can  be  verified  and  the  other  not ; 
the  one  starts  from  experience  and  returns  to  experience, 
the  other  altogether  leaves  the  region  of  experience.  The 
result  of  Lewes's  attempt  to  treat  philosophical  problems 
on  scientific  methods,  can  hardly  be  described  as  satisfac- 
toiy,  as  to  some  extent  indicated  in  the  comparatively 
small  success  which,  in  proporti(m  to  the  importance  of  its 
claims,  the  work  attained.  The  treatment  of  the  cardinal 
question  of  the  relation  of  subject  and  object,  as  one  might 
expect  from  the  standpoint  occupied,  exhibits  confusion 
between  the  scientific  fact  of  the  union  of  mental  and 
material  ]>henomena  in  one  organism,  and  the  meta- 
physical fact  of  all  phenomena  being  determinations  (jf 
consciousness. 

The  Monistic  position  is  arrived  at  in  the  form  of  an 
inference  from  the  parallelism  discoverable  between 
physical  and  psychical  processes.  This  fundamental  con- 
fusion between  the  physical  and  the  metaphysical  stand- 
points, naturally  pervades  the  treatment  of  each  of  the 
'Problems  of  Life  and  Mind.'  Lewes's  accentuation  of 
the  disiinction  between  the  ideality  of  science  and  the 
reality  of  "  common  sense "  denotes  nevertheless  an 
undoubted  abvance  on  the  previous  thought  of  the 
empirical  school. 

It  remains  now  to  give  a  somewhat  more  detailed  notice 
of  the  system  of  Herbert  Spencer,  whose  influence  has 
been  and  still  is  wide-reaching  and  considerable.  Spencer, 
like  Lewes,  Mill,  and  the  other  English  T^TL'iters  of  his 
generation,  has  been  strongly  influenced  by  the  writings 
of  A.uguste  Comte. 

'i'he  philosophy  of  Herbert  Spencer  starts  with  the 
distinction  between  the  knowable  and  the  unknowable, 
the  absolute  and  the  relative.  This  pronounced  de- 
marcation,   amounting    almost  to  dualism,   is  the  foun- 


SPENCER,  381 

dation  of  Spencer's  system.  The  first  and  smallest 
division  of  his  philosophy,  which  deals  with  the  unknow- 
able, proclaims  the  existence  of  the  Absolute  or  the 
absoluteness  of  Existence  (for  the  two  expressions  are 
in  Spencer's  case  almost  interchangeable),  outside  the 
phenomenal  world,  but  at  the  same  time  Spencer  proclaims 
our  nescience  of  all  that  concerns  this  Absolute.  Our 
very  recognition  of  the  relativitj'  of  knowledge  is 
meaningless  except  in  contradistinction  to  a  non-relative 
or  Absolute.  "We  have  seen,"  he  says  in  summing  up 
liis  argument,  "  how  in  the  very  assertion  that  all  our 
knowledge  properly  so  called  is  Eelative,  there  is  involved 
the  assertion  that  there  exists  a  Non-relative.  We  have 
seen  how,  in  each  step  of  the  argument  by  which  this 
doctrine  is  established,  the  same  assumption  is  made. 
We  have  seen  how,  from  the  very  necessity  of  thinking 
in  relation,  it  follows  that  the  Eelative  is  itself  incon- 
ceivable except  as  related  to  a  Non-relative.  We  have 
seen  that  unless  a  Non-relative  or  Absolute  be  postulated, 
the  Eelative  itself  becomes  absolute;  and  so  brings  the 
argument  to  a  contradiction.  And  on  contemplating  the 
process  of  thought,  we  have  equally  seen  how  impossible 
it  is  to  get  rid  of  the  consciousness  of  an  actuality  lying 
behind  appearances ;  and  how,  from  this  impossibility, 
results  our  indestructible  belief  in  that  actuality."  ('  First 
Principles,'  pp.  96-7.)  In  a  chapter  on  "  ultimate  scientific 
ideas,"  Herbert  Spencer  endeavours  to  show  how  all 
scientific  conceptions  rest  ultimately  on  the  insoluble. 
Matter,  force,  space,  time  on  ultimate  analysis,  abut  on 
incomprehensibility,  in  other  words,  they  commit  us  to 
what  Spencer  terms  "alternative  impossibilities  of 
thought."  He  has  already  shown  this  to  be  the  case 
with  ultimate  religious  ideas.  The  reconciliation  Spencer 
professes  to  effect  between  science  and  religion  consists 
in  the  recognition  by  the  former  of  the  existence  of  an 
Absolute  behind  phenomena,  and  by  the  latter  of  the 
absolutely  inscrutable  nature  of  this  existence.  The 
relation  of  philosophy  to  science  is  that  of  the  general 
to  the  particular ;  just  as  the  relation  of  science  to 
ordinary  knowledge  is  that  of  the  general  to  the  par- 
ticular.    "  As  each  widest  generalisation  of  science  com- 


382  MODEEN    PHILOSOPHY. 

prelicnds  and  consolidatos  the  narrower  generalisations  of 
its  own  division;  so  the  generalisations  of  Phih'Soplij- 
comprehend  and  consolidate  the  widest  generalisations  ol 
science.  It  is  therefore  a  knowledge  of  the  extreme 
opposite  in  kind  to  that  which  experience  first  accumu- 
lates. It  is  the  final  product  of  that  process  which  begins 
with  a  mere  colligation  of  crude  observations,  goes  on 
establishing  piopositions  that  are  broader  and  more  sej^a- 
rated  from  particular  cases,  and  ends  in  universal  propo- 
sitions. Or  to  bring  the  definition  to  its  simplest  and 
clearest  form : — knowledge  of  the  lowest  kind  is  un-unified 
knowledge;  science  is  2^cirtially-unified  knowledge;  philo- 
sophy is  completely -unified  knowledge."  ('  First  Princi- 
ples,'  pp.  133-4.) 

The  positive  or  constructive  side  of  the  Spencerian 
philosophy  is  based  upon  the  doctrine  of  Evolution.  The 
data  of  science,  space,  time,  matter,  motion  and  force,  are 
treated  at  the  outset  from  a  psychological  standpoint. 
The  psychological  definition  given  of  reality  is  interesting 
and  important.  "  By  reality  we  mean  persistence  in 
consciousness  :  a  persistence  that  is  either  unconditional, 
as  our  consciousness  of  space,  or,  that  is  conditional,  as  our 
consciousness  of  a  body  while  grasj^ing  it.  The  real,  as 
we  conceive  it,  is  distinguished  solely  by  the  test  of 
persistence ;  for  by  this  test  we  separate  it  from  what  we 
call  the  unreal."  On  the  strength  of  this  definition 
conjoined  wdth  what  has  preceded,  the  conclusion  is  once 
more  drawn  that  we  have  "  an  indefinite  consciousness  of 
an  absolute  reality  transcending  relations,  which  is  pro- 
dnced  by  the  absolute  persistence  in  us  of  something 
which  survives  all  changes  of  relation."  Also,  that  we 
have  a  definite  reality,  which  unceasingly  persists  in  us, 
under  one  or  other  of  its  forms,  and  under  each  form  so 
long  as  the  conditions  of  presentation  are  fulfilled.  The 
distinction  between  the  two  is  consequently  not  one  as 
between  greater  and  less  reality,  for  both  are  alike  real, 
but  between  two  different  kinds  of  leality. 

Spencer's  test  of  truth — the  ultimate  criterion  in  philo- 
sophy— is  the  "  inconceivability  of  the  opposite  ;  "  that 
is  to  say,  where  the  opposite  of  a  given  proposition  is 
inconceivable,  that  proposition  is  true.    This,  be  it  observed, 


SfENCEIi.  3S3 

is  only  a  roundabout  way  of  affirniiug  that  self-consistency 
of  thought  on  -which  the  speculative  or  generic  method  is 
founded.  Reality  has  already  been  defined  as  persistence 
in  consciousness ;  on  the  strength  of  this,  Spencer  is  of 
course  a  realist.  He  terms  his  doctrine  transfigured  realism 
as  opposed  to  the  naive  realism  of  popular  conception. 
The  "  indestructibilit}^  of  matter,"  like  the  "  persistence 
of  force,"  is  deduced  from  the  fundamental  postulate  of 
the  "inconceivability  of  the  opp(»site,"  the  contrary  of 
each  of  the.se  assumptions  being  shown  to  involve  an 
impossibility  of  thought.  No  less  axiomatic  is  the  idea 
of  the  continuity  of  motion.  "  The  first  deduction," 
says  Spencer,  "  to  be  drawn  from  the  ultimate  universal 
truth  that  force  persists,  is  that  the  relations  among 
forces  persist.  Supposing  a  given  manifestation  of 
force,  under  a  given  form  and  given  conditions,  be 
either  preceded  by,  or  succeeded  by  some  other  manifesta- 
tion, it  must,  in  all  cases  where  the  form  and  conditions 
are  the  same,  be  preceded  by  or  succeeded  by  such  other 
manifestation.  Every  antecedent  mode  of  the  Unknow- 
able must  have  an  invariable  connection,  quantita- 
tive and  qualitative,  with  that  mode  of  the  Unknowable 
which  we  call  its  consequent.  For  to  say  otherwise  is  to 
deny  the  persistence  of  force.  If  in  any  two  cases  there 
is  exact  likeness,  not  only  between  those  most  conspicuous 
antecedents,  which  we  distinguish  as  the  causes,  but  also 
between  those  accompanying  antecedents,  which  we  call 
the  conditions,  we  cannot  affirm  that  the  effects  will  differ, 
without  affirming  either  that  some  force  has  come  into 
existence  or  that  some  force  has  ceased  to  exist.  If  the 
co-operative  forces  in  the  one  case  are  equal  to  those  in  the 
other,  each  to  each,  in  distribution  and  amount,  then  it  is 
impossible  to  conceive  the  product  of  their  joint  action  in 
the  one  case  as  unlike  that  in  the  other,  without  con- 
ceiving one  or  more  of  the  forces  to  have  increased  or 
diminished  in  quantity ;  and  this  is  conceiving  that  force  is 
not  persistent."    ('  First  Principles,'  p.  193.) 

The  transformation  and  equivalence  of  force,  the  direction 
of  motion,  which  is  shown  to  be  in  the  line  of  least  resis- 
tance and  in  the  direction  of  the  greatest  force ;  the 
Thythm   of  motion,  by   which  is  meant   the  oscillations 


384  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY. 

invariably  accompanying  motion  in  every  department  of 
phenomena,  are  deduced  fiom  the  ultimate  principle  of  the 
Persistence  of  force.  1  hese  things  are  what  Spencer  terms 
the  components  of  phenomena.  It  now  remains,  after 
"  having  seen  that  matter  is  indestructible,  motion  con- 
tinuous, and  force  persistent ;  having  seen  that  forces  are 
everywhere  undergoing  transformation,  and  that  motion, 
always  following  the  line  of  least  resistance,  is  invariably 
rhythmic ;  it  remains  to  discover  the  similarly  invariable 
formula  expressing  the  combined  consequences  of  the 
actions  thus  separately  formulated."  The  formula  sought 
may  be  defined  as  the  law  of  the  continuous  redistribution  of 
matter  and  motion.  All  objects  individually  and  collec- 
tively are  undergoing  every  instant  some  change  of  state. 
In  other  words  they  are  absorbing  motion  or  losing  motion. 
The  question  to  be  answered  is  therefore  what  dynamic 
principle  obtaining  at  once  in  general  and  detail,  expresses 
this  constant  change  of  relation. 

All  processes  of  change  may  be  divided  into  two  classes, 
those  of  integration  or  evolution,  and  those  of  dis- 
integration or  dissolution.  Evolution  always  means  in 
the  last  resort  the  concentration  of  matter  accompanied  by 
the  dissipation  of  motion ;  while  dissolution  means  the 
reverse  process,  that  is,  the  diffubion  of  matter  and  the 
absorption  of  motion.  One  or  other  of  these  processes  is 
going  on  in  every  perceived  whole.  Evolution  may  be 
furtlier  described  as  the  progress  from  an  indefinite  and 
homogeneous  state  to  a  definite  and  heterogeneous  state. 

Evolution  may  be  simple  or  compound.  Where  the 
onl}^  forces  at  work  are  those  directly  tending  to  produce 
aggregation  or  diffusion,  there  will  be  no  more  than  the 
approach  of  the  components  of  the  aggregate  or  whole 
towards  the  common  centre ;  in  other  words,  the  process 
of  evolution  will  be  simple  ;  such  will  be  the  case,  more- 
over, where  the  forces  tending  towards  the  centre  are 
greatly  in  excess  of  other  forces ;  or  when,  on  account  of 
the  smallness  of  the  mass,  or  the  smallness  of  the  quantity 
of  motion  it  receives  from  without,  the  process  proceeds 
rapidly.  But  when,  on  the  contrary,  from  whatever 
cause,  the  process  proceeds  slowly,  then  the  mass  will  be 
appreciably   modified   by   other   forces.      In   addition   to 


SPENCER.  885 

the  chief  primary  change  of  integration,  secondary  and 
supplementary  changes  will  be  produced ;  the  process  of 
evolution  will,  in  other  words,  be  compound.  This 
principle  Spencer  proceeds  to  illustrate  at  length  in 
the  course  of  the  discussion,  some  important  facts  being 
brought  out,  as  that  the  quantity  of  secondarj'  redistribu- 
tion in  an  organism  varies  according  to  the  contained 
quantity  of  the  motion  we  call  heat,  &c.  The  principles 
of  evolution  are  then  discussed  in  detail ;  first,  in  their 
primary  aspect  of  simple  evolution,  and  afterwards  more 
especially  with  respect  to  the  secondary  redistributions 
constituting  compound  evolution. 

It  having  been  shown  that  all  existences  must  reach 
their  ultimate  shape  through  processes  of  concentration. 
it  remains  for  Spencer  to  show  how  different  orders  of 
phenomena  do  actually  exhibit  the  process  of  the  integra- 
tion of  matter,  and  the  dissipation  of  motion.  "  Tracing, 
so  far  as  we  may  by  observation  and  inference,  the  objects 
dealt  with  by  the  Astronomer  and  the  Geologist,  as  w^ell 
as  those  which  Biology,  Psychology  and  Sociology  treat 
of,  we  have  to  consider  what  direct  proof  there  is  that  the 
Cosmos,  in  general  and  in  detail,  conforms  to  this  law." 
In  the  course  of  the  ensuing  discussion  it  is  shown  that 
the  same  process  is  going  on  in  the  several  parts  or 
members  of  aggregates,  as  in  the  wholes.  Thus,  while 
there  has  been  a  gradual  concentration  of  the  Solar 
system  from  its  primitive  nebulous  state,  there  has  been 
none  the  less  a  concentration  going  on  in  each  planet. 
The  same  applies  to  the  geological  development  of  the 
earth  regarded  as  itself  an  aggregate  ;  to  that  of  the 
animal  from  the  embryo ;  to  the  differentiation  of  species 
and  to  the  development  of  society.  ''  Alike  during  the 
evolution  of  the  Solar  system,  of  a  planet,  of  an  organism, 
of  a  nation,  there  is  progressive  aggregation  of  the  entire 
mass.  This  may  be  shown  by  the  increasing  density  of 
the  matter  already  contained  in  it ;  or  by  the  drawing 
into  it  of  matter  that  was  before  separate,  or  by  both. 
But  in  any  case  it  implies  a  loss  of  relative  motion.  At 
the  same  time,  the  parts  into  which  the  mass  has  divided, 
severally  consolidate  in  like  manner.  We  see  this  in 
that  formation  of  planets  and  satellites  which  has  gone 

2  c 


386  MODERN    PHILOSOPHY. 

on  along  witli  the  concentration  of  the  nebula  out  of 
which  the  Solar  system  originated ;  we  see  it  in  the 
growth  of  separate  organs  that  advances,  pari  passu,  with 
the  growth  of  each  organism ;  we  see  it  in  that  rise  of 
special  industrial  centres,  and  special  masses  of  population, 
which  is  associated  with  the  rise  of  each  society.  Always 
more  or  less  of  local  integration  accompanies  the  general 
integration.  And  then,  beyond  the  incieased  closeness 
of  juxtaposition  among  the  components  of  the  whole,  and 
among  the  components  of  each  part,  there  is  increased 
closeness  of  combination  among  the  parts,  producing 
mutual  dependence  of  them."  ('  First  Principles,'  p.  328.) 

The  secondary  process  which  accompanies  the  primary 
in  evolution  may  be  formulated  as  one  from  the  homo- 
geneous and  indefinite  to  the  heterogeneous  and  definite. 
Spencer  shows  this  exhaustively  a  posteriori  in  the 
departments  of  Astronomy,  Geology,  Biology,  Philology, 
Psychology,  and  Sociology,  &c.  In  the  chapter  on  the 
*'  instability  of  the  homogeneous,"  is  illustrated  with 
characteristic  wealth  of  examples  the  tendency  of  the 
homogeneous  and  indefinite  towards  change  ;  how  impos- 
sible is  the  continuance  of  an  aggregate  in  the  state  of 
homogeneity.  Another  factor  in  the  evolutionary  process 
is  the  "  multiplication  of  eifects,"  that  is,  the  tendency  of 
the  incident  force  acting  upon  a  uniform  aggregate  to 
become  itself  differentiated  in  a  ratio  corresponding  with 
the  differentiation  of  the  aggregate.  Thus,  when  one 
body  is  struck  against  another,  besides  the  visible 
mechanical  result,  sound,  or  a  vibration  in  the  bodies  and 
in  the  surrounding  air,  is  produced  ;  the  air  has  moreover 
had  currents  raided  in  it  by  the  passage  of  the  bodies 
through  it ;  there  is  a  disarrangement  of  particles  of  the 
bodies  around  their  point  of  collision  ;  heat  is  disengaged; 
in  some  cases  a  spark  or  light  is  produced  by  the  incan- 
descence of  a  portion,  while  occasionally  this  is  associated 
with  chemical  combination.  "  Thus,"  says  Spencer,  "  by 
the  original  mechanical  force  expended  in  the  collision, 
at  least,  five  and  often  more  different  kinds  of  forces  have 
been  produced." 

Thus  far  an  explanation  has  been  afforded  of  the 
change   from   homogeneity   to   heterogeneity,   from  uni- 


SPENCER.  ^87 

formity  to  miilfiforinity  ;  but  tlic8e  explanations  do  not, 
of  themselves,  accoimt  for  the  change  from  indefiniteness 
to  definiteness.  The  ground  of  explanation  of  this  is  to 
be  found  in  the  principle  of  "  Segregation."  This 
principle  of  Segregation,  by  which  is  meant  the  union 
of  like  with  like,  and  a  consequent  separation  from  the 
unlike,  may  be  variously  illustrated ;  a  strong  wind  in 
the  autumn  sweeps  the  dead  leaves  in  masses  to  the 
ground,  while  the  living  are  left  on  the  trees ;  a  similar 
process  takes  place  in  the  separation  of  dust  and  sand 
from  small  stones,  as  we  may  see  on  any  road  in  March. 
In  every  river,  again,  the  materials  are  deposited  in 
separate  layers — boulders,  pebbles,  sand  and  mud.  The 
winnowing  of  chaff  from  wheat  also  illustrates  this 
principle,  which  is  of  common  application  in  the  indus- 
trial arts.  Spencer  as  usual  traces  it  through  the  several 
orders  of  phenomena,  from  the  Astronomical  to  the 
Social. 

With  the  principle  of  Segregation,  the  discussion  on  the 
factors  constituting  Evolution  is  terminated.  The  next 
question  is  as  to  the  final  goal  of  the  evolutionary  process. 
Does  this  process  go  on  for  ever,  or  is  there  a  point 
beyond  which  it  can  proceed  no  farther?  Spencer  replies 
that  there  is  such  a  point : — in  short,  that  all  evolution 
tends  toward  equilibration  ;  that  it  finally  comes  to  anchor 
in  absolute  quiescence  or  equilibrium.  The  last  point  is 
illustrated,  in  the  usual  manner,  and  it  is  then  shown  how 
all  this  is  a  deduction  from  the  primary  principle  of  the 
persistence  of  force.  "  Thus  from  the  persistence  of  force 
follows  not  only  the  various  direct  and  indirect  equilibra- 
tions going  on  around,  together  with  that  cosmical  equili- 
bration which  brings  Evolution  under  all  its  forms  to  a 
close ;  but  also  those  less  manifest  equilibrations  shown  in 
the  readjustments  of  moving  equilibria  that  have  been 
ed  listurbed.  By  this  ultimate  principle  is  provable  the 
by  tendency  of  every  organism,  disordered  by  some  unusual 
nfluence,  to  return  to  a  balanced  state.  To  it  also  may 
36  traced  the  capacity,  possessed  in  a  slight  degree  by 
ndividuals,  and  in  a  greater  degree  by  species,  of  becoming 
idapted  to  new  circumstances.  And  not  less  does  it 
fford   a  basis  for  the  inference,  that  there  is  a  gradual 

0  2 


8-8  MODERN    PHILOSOPHY. 

advance  towards  harmony  between  man's  mental  nature 
and  the  conditions  of  his  existence.  After  finding  that 
from  it  are  dedncible  the  various  characteristics  of 
Evolution,  we  finally-  draw  from  it  a  warrant  for  the  be- 
lief, that  Evolution  can  end  only  in  the  establishment  of 
the  greatest  perfection  and  the  most  complete  happiness." 
('First  Principles,'  p.  517.) 

Lastly  remains  the  question  of  dissolution.  The 
equilibrium  once  attained,  the  point  having  been  reached 
when  evolution  ceases,  the  tendency  must  always  be  to  a 
reversal  of  the  process.  All  change  henceforth  must  be 
in  the  direction  of  disintegration,  of  dissolution.  This, 
which  is  illustrated  in  detail  by  the  life  and  death  of 
planetary  systems,  of  individual  animals,  of  societies,  &c., 
is  true  no  less  of  the  nniverse  as  a  whole;  this  also,  on 
the  foregoing  principles — its  evolutionary  process  having 
reached  its  term — must  tend  to  dissolution.  This  portion 
of  the  'First  Principles'  recalls  to  our  mind  the  theories 
of  the  early  Greek  speculators,  of  Herakleitos,  Empedokles, 
and  Anaxagoras,  &c.,  with  their  eternally  alternating 
processes  of  world-formation  and  destruction.  For 
though  Herbert  Spencer  finds  Universal  Evolution  to 
point  to  Universal  Dissolution,  yet  this  latter  itself, 
none  the  less,  foreshadows  a  recommencement  of  the 
proces.s,  on  the  same  reasoning.  The  summary  and  con- 
cdusion  of  the  '  First  Principles  '  consists  of  a  restatement 
of  the  doctrine  of  the  Unknowable  in  antithesis  to  the 
Knowable  with  which  the  book  opened.  "  Over  and  over 
again  it  has  been  shovkTi,  in  various  ways,  that  the  deepest 
truths  we  can  reach,  are  simply  statements  of  the  widest 
uniformities  in  our  experience  of  the  relations  of  Matter, 
Motion,  and  Force,  and  that  Matter,  ^lotion,  and  Ft^rce 
are  but  symbols  of  the  Unknown  Ee  ility." 

We  refrain  ftom  entering  on  the  carrying  out  of  the 
"  first  jDrinciples  "  indicated  in  the  foregoing  pages,  in 
detail  in  the  departments  of  Biology,  Psychology,  So- 
ciology, &c.,  as  embodied  in  the  later  works  of  Herbert 
Spencer.  The  '  Principles  of  Biologj^ '  is  universally 
admitted  to  be  a  masterpiece  of  scientific  generalization ; 
but  we  venture  to  think  that  Herbert  Spencer's  most 
devoted   admirers   will   hardly   seriously  deny  that  the 


SPENCER.  389 

'  Principles  of  Sociolog:y  '  shows  a  falling  off— a  falling  off 
which  others  might  add,  that  results  in  an  inadec^uacy  of 
treatment  verging  at  times  on  the  pueiile. 

Of  Herbert  Spencer's  great  powers  fis  a  generalizer  of 
the  results  of  modern  scientific  thonght,  there  can  be  no 
doubt.  These  powers  he  indeed  possesses  in  an  almost 
unique  degree,  but  side  by  side  with  them,  we  find  a  total 
incapacity  to  appreciate  modes  of  thought  foreign  to  the 
special  grooves  in  which  his  way  of  speculative  life  has 
been  cast.  The  most  flabbjT-  pretences  of  the  Laissez-faire 
economy  are  argued  from  as  dogmas  universally  accepted, 
to  dispute  which  is  imj)ious,  much  in  the  same  way  as 
the  Methodist  preacher  argues  from  the  dogmas  of 
his  Calvinistic  theology. 

Again,  his  attempted  reconciliation  of  Science  and 
Theology,  of  Materialism  and  Idealism,  on  the  basis 
of  a  mechanically  conceived  abstiact  Monism,  betrays  a 
crudity  of  conception  which  argues  a  strange  lack  of  the 
speculative  faculty.  This  is  confirmed  by  the  singular 
ignoratio  elenchi  involved  in  his  would-be  refutations  of 
the  Germans.  But  Spencer  is  n<  t  always  consistent  with 
himself  in  treating  of  the  abstractum  he  has  set  up  as  a 
receptacle  for  "religious  sentiment,"  "ultimate  facts,"  &c. 
The  Positivists  and  the  orthodox  Empiricists  would  fling 
aside  the  metaphysical  problem  altogether.  Herbert 
Spencer  provides  a  home  for  it  in  the  bosom  of  the 
Unknowable.  We  say  the  Unknowable,  since  Spencer 
tells  us  that  the  Absolute  is  unknowable;  but,  strangely 
enough,  it  reappears  on  occasion  in  guises  not  quite  so 
unknowable  as  they  might  be.  The  most  usual  shape 
which  it  assumes  in  the  course  of  the  exposition  is 
Force — the  force  behind  phenomena — which  is  manifested 
to  us  in  the  phenomena  themselves.  Yet  another  time  it  is 
insi.'^ted  upon  that  it  is  not  to  be  identified  either  with  the 
sj)iritual  or  mateiial  sides  of  the  phenomenal  world — the 
world  of  relativity— although  it  is  the  ground-princi23le  of 
them  both.  The  Spencerite  Unknowable,  view  it  as  we 
may,  is  a  surd  entirely  cut  off  from  the  sj-stem  of  ex- 
perience, notwithstanding  that  it  is  the  cause  of  the 
phenomena  given  in  experience. 

The  influence  of  Herbert  Spencer's  system  has  been  very 


390  MODEKN   PHILOSOPKY. 

Avide.  In  tin's  country  and  America  lie  is  pre-eminently 
the  philosopher.  His  very  failings  no  less  than  his  merits 
contribute  to  his  popularity  among  the  English-speaking 
races ;  but  indeed  the  importance  of  the  cosmical  truths 
Herbert  Spencer  has  taught  might  well  blind  many  of  his 
admirers  to  his  defects. 

The  supremacy  of  the  orthodox  Biitish  Philosophy, 
Empiiicism,  like  the  orthodox  British  economy  Laissez- 
faire,  has  been  rudely  shaken  of  late.  The  one  doctrine 
like  the  other  has  been  practically  driven  to  adopt  the 
defensive.  In  philosophy  the  new  movement  has  been  at 
present  chiefly  confined  to  academical  circles,  but  it  is 
already  beginning  to  extend  itself  beyond  this  necessarily 
limited  area.  The  characteristic  of  this  movement  is  the 
attempt  to  rehabilitate  in  this  country  philosophy  proper, 
that  is  the  great  problem  as  to  the  constitution  of  ex- 
perience or  reality,  which  occupied  the  attention  of  Plato 
and  Aristotle  in  the  ancient  world  and  which  was  revived 
in  its  full  meaning  by  the  main  line  of  the  German  post- 
Kantian  thinkers.  Among  the  names  most  prominently 
connected  with  this  movement  may  be  mentioned  those 
of  Eobert  Adamson,  Edward  Caird,  the  late  T.  H.  Green, 
E.  B.  and  J.  S.  Haldane,  Andrew  Seth,  William  and 
Edwin  Wallace,  &c.  These  writers,  though  diiiering  in 
some  respects  among  each  other,  have  all  made  it  their 
task  to  present  in  as  intelligible  a  form  as  possible  to  the 
English  mind  the  principle  of  the  speculative  method,  and 
to  state  in  clear  terms  the  problem  which  "  speculation  " 
or  "theory  of  knowledge"  has  to  resolve — that  namely 
as  to  the  meaning  and  constitution  of  reality.  This  school 
is  sometimes  called  the  Neo-Hegelian  school;  and  its 
doctrine  may  be  said  to  consist  in  a  restatement  of  the 
philosophical  positions  of  the  Hegelian  right.  We  have 
already  (pp.  3i5-3ol)  indicated  what  we  conceived  to  be 
the  shortcoming  of  this  standpoint.  This  shortcoming  we 
do  not  think  is  obviated  in  the  more  recent  statement 
of  the  doctrine.  Briefly  expressed,  it  is  as  follows  :  In  the 
synthetic  unity  of  consciousness  it  is  said  the  opposition 
of  the  momenta  of  matter  and  form,  potentiality  and 
actuality,  &c.,  immanent  in  consciousness — i.e.  the    most 


NEO-IIEG ELIAN    SCHOOL.  391 

ultimate  vf  all  oppositions — is  transcended.  This  being  ad- 
mitted, it  is  contending  that  the  Iieal  consists  in  a  synthesis 
of  positive  tlionght-determinations  alone,  in  other  words, 
the  position  corresponds  to  that  of  Plato — the  system  of 
ideas  subsumed  under  the  supreme  idea  ;  or  that  of  Aristotle 
— the  "creative  intellect,"  the  actus  purus  or  first  principle 
of  pure  form  which  knowledge  presupposes.  The  present 
writer  would  suggest  that  so  far  from  the  opposition  being 
transcended  in  the  ultimate  unity  of  the  consciousness,  it 
rather  finds  therein  its  supreme  expression  as  the  distinc- 
tion between  consciousness  and  its  sul)ject,  between  the  1 
of  apperception  and  the  think  of  apperception,  or,  otherwise 
ex2:)ressed,  between  the  primal  thatness  and  the  primal  ivhat- 
ness*  From  this  ultimate  expression  of  the  antithesis  of 
matter  and  form  all  other  expressions  of  the  same  antithesis 
are  deducible.  The  final  interpretation  of  the  universe  is 
thus  pure  potentiality.  One  other  point.  The  concep- 
tion of  the  world-synthesis  as  pure  actuality  naturally 
leads  to  the  dogma  of  the  completed  realisation  of  the 
world-principle  in  man  as  organic  individual,  in  other 
words,  in  the  individual  mind  or  soul.  Nature  on  this 
view  comes  to  a  complete  knowledge  of  herself  in  the 
present  human  consciousness  ;  but  have  we  any  right  to 
make  such  an  assumption?  Is  such  an  assumption  com- 
patible with  a  recognition  of  the  social  pur2")0se  implied  in 
the  moral  tendency  ?  Does  not  this  imply  that  the  organic 
synthesis,  the  human  individual,  the  self-realisation  of 
nature  is  as  yet  incomplete,  and  awaits  a  higher  de\'elop- 
ment?  Such  a  conception  as  that  here  hinted  at  it  is 
difficult  to  represent  to  one's  self  in  thought,  much  more 
to  express  in  words,  but  the  suggestion  will  not  be  an 
altogether  useless  one,  even  though  it  merely  acts  as  what 
Kant  would  have  termed  a  limitative  notion  in  checking 
the  dogmatic  assumption  above  noticed. 

It  may  also  jDOssibly  have  some  bearing  in  connection 
with  an  objection  which  Professor  Caird  observes  (art. 
"  Metaphysic,"  Encyc.  Brit ,  9th  ed.)  is  frequently  urged 
against  an  Hegelian  Metaphysic  :  "  The  great  objection  to 

*  Of  course  the  thatness  here  spnken  of  is  not  equivalent  to  the 
emptiness  of  the  concept  pure  being,  inasmuch  as  it  has  a  determination, 
that  of  constituting  tlie  ground-principle  ox ])ossihility  of  consciousness. 


392  MODERN    PHILOSOPHY. 

a  inetapliysic  like  this,  at  least  an  objection  which  weighs 
much  in  the  minds  of  many,  is  that  which  springs  from 
the  contrast  between  the  claim  of  absolute  knowledge 
which  it  seems  to  involve,  and  the  actual  limitations  which 
our  intelligence  encounters  in  every  direction.  If  the 
theory  were  true,  it  is  felt  we  ought  to  be  nearer  the 
solution  of  the  problems  of  our  life,  practical  and  specula- 
tive, than  we  are  ;  the  riddle  of  the  painful  earth  ought  to 
vex  us  less ;  we  ought  to  find  our  way  more  easily  through 
the  entanglement  of  facts,  and  to  be  able  to  deal  with 
practical  difficulties  in  a  less  tentative  manner."  This 
conception  of  the  world-synthesis  as  form  and  actuality, 
and  of  its  final  realisation  in  the  psychological  unity 
re^Dresented  by  the  organic  individual,  has,  we  think,  much 
to  do  with  the  apparent  opposition  of  Hegelianism  not  only 
to  common-sense  but  also  to  the  scientific  intellect.  Let 
us  take  an  instance  of  the  inadequacy  of  the  last-mentioned 
point  of  view  from  the  treatment  it  involves  of  the  problem 
of  liberty  and  necessity.  "  Man,"  says  Professor  Caird,  "  is 
determined'  by  his  desires  only  so  far  as  he  makes  their 
object  his  object,  or  seeks  his  own  satisfaction  in  them. 
\Ve  may  admit  that  there  is  a  sense  in  which  the  common 
spying  is  true  that  a  man's  action  is  the  result  of  his 
character  and  circumstances.  But  this  does  not  make 
him  a  necessary  agent ;  for  the  cii-cumstances  are  what 
they  are  for  him  by  the  action  of  consciousness,  and  the 
character  is  the  man  as  he  has  framed  to  himself  an  idea 
of  good,  of  a  universe  of  satisfactions,  in  which  he  seeks 
to  be  realised."  ('Mind,'  vol.  vi.  p.  550.)  In  the  argu- 
ment of  which  this  passage  is  a  sample,  ihe  action  of  the 
social  medium  in  framing  for  the  man  the  universe  of 
satisfactions  referred  to  is  entirely  ignored.  The  *'  idea  of 
good  "  is  regarded  as  framed  by  the  man  himself,  rather 
than  by  the  social  whole,  past  and  present,  into  which  he 
enters.  The  formal  principle,  consciousness,  as  such,  is 
moreover  treated  as  per  se  creative. 

Now  it  may  with  fairness  be  contended  that  the  man  does 
xiot  identify  the  desired  object  with  himself,  as  the  late 
Professor  Green  would  have  it,  by  any  conscious  act  of  self- 
determination  on  his  part,  but  that  with  his  mental 
concept  of  the  object  is  already  given  the  notion  of  it  as 


NEO-IIEG ELIAN   SCHOOL.  393 

an  "  end,"  which,  if  not  counterbalanced  by  the  presence  of 
other  more  potent  ends,  dotei  mines  his  action,  a  fact  which 
is  registered  in  the  empirical  consciousness,  together  with 
the  correlative  possihilify  of  other  ends  having  under  other 
circumst  inces  become  motives,  which  formal  registration 
we  term  Freedom  !  But  notwithstanding  all  criticism,  the 
usefulness  of  the  work  done  by  these  writers  for  English 
students  of  philosophy  can  hardly  be  oveirated.*  The 
Neo-Hegelians,  even  if  they  have  not  said  the  last  word 
on  the  speculative  problem,  are  ])y  far  the  most  important 
school  existing  at  present.  The  fact  that  they  have  intro- 
duced the  sjieculative  problem  at  all  to  the  English 
reading  public  is  of  itself  a  by  no  means  insignificant 
service.  The  writings  of  the  school  form  the  best  possible 
introduction  to  Philosophy,  and  at  least  furnish  a  basis 
for  the  discussion  of  its  problems,  which  did  not  exist 
before  outside  Germany. 

*  There  is  one  point  upon  which  we  would  like  to  hear  an  explana- 
tion from  one  of  the  authoiitative  leaders  of  the  more  pronouncedly 
right  wing  of  the  school — that  is,  as  to  the  theolo^acul  terminology 
affected,  and  especially  as  to  the  employment  of  the  word  "God!" 
On  the  principles  admitted  by  Professor  Caird,  for  example,  this 
word,  as  popularly  used,  implies  an  antithesis  to  Nature  and  Man  ;  it 
is  used  to  express  the  opposition  of  finite  and  infiuite.  This,  we  take  it, 
will  not  be  tienied.  Now  we  would  ask,  by  what  right  is  a  term  sug- 
gestive of,  and  associated  with,  the  most  decisive  aspect  of  the  opposi- 
tion employed  in  a  connection  where  the  opposition  is  abolished?  A 
similar  line  miyht  be  taken  up  as  regards  the  reading  of  Hegeliani.'im 
into  Christian  dogmas. 


394  MODERN    PHILOSOPHZ. 


CONCLUSION. 


In  tlie  course  of  the  history  we  have  just  traversed,  the 
ordinary  reader  may  see  little  but  a  chaos  of  theories. 
fSuch  a  view,  however,  can  only  obtain  where  a  super- 
ficial glance  has  been  taken  of  the  whole.  We  have 
again  and  again  had  occasion  to  point  out  the  continuous 
reappearance  of  the  same  doctrines  in  thinkers,  widely 
separated  in  time  and  intellectual  surroundings,  and  who 
approached  the  problem  from  altogether  different  and 
even  opposed  standpoints.  Such  indications  of  what  to 
the  superficial  reader  might  appear  coincidences  could 
have  been  almost  indefinitely  multiplied.  This  of  itself 
would  lead  to  the  suspicion  of  a  central  truth  around 
which  the  most  seemingly  antagonistic  philosophies  were 
revolving.  The  History  of  Philosophy  is  indeed  no 
medley  of  mere  opinions,  but  represents  in  various  guises, 
determined  immediately  by  personality,  age,  surroundings, 
&c.,  the  several  stages  through  which  the  human  mind 
must  pass  in  its  endeavours  to  arrive  at  the  complete  for- 
mulation of  the  world-problem,  together  with  its  solution, 
which  is  nothing  other  than  the  final  rational  exj)lanation 
of  the  world.  By  the  last  expression  is  me;mt  an  expla- 
nation which,  while  it  includes  all  other  explanations 
attained  from  more  limited  points  of  view,  yet  neverthe- 
less transcends  them.  Philosophy  in  the  exact  sense  of 
the  word — philosophy  jpar  excellence — is,  in  short,  the  final 
and  most  comprehensive  interpretation  of  Eeality.  It  is 
not  a  theory  of  how  things  may  be,  but  the  theory  of  how 
tilings  are. 

Strictly  speaking,  we  have  no  right  to  talk  of  philo- 
sop>hies  at  all,  any  more  than  we  have  to  talk  of  chemistries 
or  physiologies.     The  history  of  Chemistry  shows  us  a 


CONCLUSION.  395 

series  of  attempts  more  or  less  crude,  more  or  less  success- 
ful, to  treat  the  problem  of  chemistry,  i.e.  the  constitutioa 
of  bodies ;  similarly  the  history  of  iiiolop^y  offers  a  series 
of  attempts  to  treat  the  problem  of  Biolojzy,  i.e.  to 
arrive  at  the  theory  (the  most  perfect  interpretation  or 
explanation)  of  organic  matter  as  such.  But  we  do  not, 
nevertheless  (nor  would  it  have  been  fair  to  do  so  for 
that  matter,  even  in  the  days  of  "  Phlogiston,"  or  of  the 
*'  animal  spirits"),  regard  Cliemistry  or  Biology  as  a  body 
of  more  or  less  probable  or  improbable  opinion;  and 
this,  notwitlistanding  the  divergences  of  view  existing 
among  scientific  specialists  in  many  cases  on  essential 
points  in  their  respective  sciences,  even  at  the  present 
day.  We  have  no  more  right  to  regard  philosophy  as 
simply  made  up  of  a  mass  of  conjectural  theories.  There 
is  but  one  Philosophy  as  thei'e  is  but  one  Science;  the 
history  of  philosofihy,  we  again  repeat,  is  the  history  of 
the  struggles  of  the  human  mind  to  attain  the  truth  of 
philosophy,  that  is  the  philosophic  point  of  view. 

It  is  important  in  dealing  with  the  history  of  philosophy 
always  to  distinguish  between  those  systems  or  parts  of 
systems  which  mark  distinct  steps  in  the  analysis  of 
experience  and  in  the  recognition  of  its  meaning,  and  those 
which  are  traceable  merely  to  some  bias  of  nationality, 
religion,  or  personal  temperament ;  the  former  alone  have 
any  true  significance  for  history.  Ordinary  electicism  or 
syncretism  pretends  to  find  philosophic  truth  implied  or 
expressed  in  all  systems  collectively,  forgetful  of  the  fact 
that  philosophic  reason  or  thought  is  always  adulterated 
more  or  less  with  local  temporary  or  personal  prejudice, 
and  that  the  true  philosophic  insight  msij  quite  possibly 
be  whoU}^  absent  from  any  particular  system.  Emerson's 
distinction  between  man  thinking  and  the  theologian, 
the  attorney  or  the  scholar  thinking,  applies  here  if  any- 
where. Here,  more  even  than  elsewhere  in  the  attainment 
of  truth,  it  is  only  where  the  individual  thinker  becomes 
the  mere  exponent  of  the  universal  thought  that  a  genuine 
insight  is  obtained.  Only  in  very  exceptional  cases  has 
such  an  insight  extended  even  imperfectly  over  the  whole 
range  of  the  philosonhic  problem;  far  oftener  it  has  only 
been  a  glimpse  of  a  particular  asjoect  of  that  problem  that 


396  MODEKN    PHILOSOPHY. 

has  been  seized.  What  is  more,  such  is  the  difficulty  of 
keeping  the  true  nature  of  the  problem  and  its  interpreta- 
tion Avithin  the  intellectual  purview,  that  although  it 
has  been  disclo.-ed  in  its  main  outline  more  than  once  in 
the  history  of  speculation,  the  effect  of  such  disclosure  has 
been  like  that  of  a  flash  of  lightning — it  has  seemed  only 
to  leave  a  more  impenetrable  subsequent  darkness.  Plato, 
Aristotle,  Spinoza,  and  the  post-Kantian  thinkers  of 
Germany,  of  whom  it  is  usual  to  take  Hegel  as  the  type, 
severally  had  the  soluti<'n  of  the  problem  within  their 
grasp,  but  the  inner  meaning  of  the  systems  of  these 
thinkers  was  imperfectly  seized  by  their  successors,  and 
in  some  cases  altogether  lost.  A  crucial  instance  of  this  is 
the  treatment  of  Aristotle  by  the  schoolmen  with  whom, 
for  the  most  part,  he  was  whittled  down  to  a  mere 
Psychologist  and  formal  Logician.  As  regards  Spinoza, 
it  mu!-t  be  admitted  that  the  abstract  dogmatic  mould  in 
which  he  cast  his  speculation,  almost  courted  miscon- 
ception from  the  first;  yet  this  can  be  hardly  said  of 
Hegel,  who  is,  nevertheless,  to  the  "  popular"  no  less  than 
to  the  "scientific"  mind  a  kind  of  subjective  idealist  who 
would  make  his  own  individual  thoughts  the  criteria  of 
things.  The  above  explains  the  charge  of  circularity  of 
movement  brought  by  scientist  thinkers  against  philo- 
sophy. While  science,  it  is  said,  ceaselessly  progresses, 
Philosophy  is  alwaj^s  returning  to  the  same  point. 
A  very  obvious  explanation  of  this  is,  that  the  difficulty 
involved  in  the  mind's  seizure  and  retention  of  the 
philosophical  point  of  view  in  its  completeness,  is  so  much 
greater,  that  in  the  case  of  the  more  limited  doctrine 
of  Phy.^ical  Science,  and  also  that  in  the  case  of  philo- 
sophy where  the  completeness  of  the  view  is  lost,  the 
point  of  vantage  gained  is  itself  apt  to  be  lost  altogether. 
Speculation  in  this  case  goes  stumbling  back  into  the  old 
beaten  paths  to  which  it  had  been  accustomed,  which  lay 
below  and  around  the  true  jDhilosophical  point  of  view, 
and  it  is  not  until  another  speculative  genius  arises  that 
the  lost  t^tandpoint  is  recovered.  There  is  gain  of  course 
in  this  seeming  fluctuation ;  each  time  that  the  synthesis 
of  philosophy  reappears  it  is  enriched;  it  is  clearer,  more 
explicit,  possessed  of  a  fuller  content. 


CONCLUSION.  397 

The  common  notion  is  that  Science  and  Philosophy  or 
metaphj'sic,  represent  two  rival  theories  of  the  universe — 
two  not  merely  opposed  but  mutually  incompatible 
methods  of  approaching  one  problem.  Nothing  can  be 
farther  from  the  tiuth.  Tlie  problem  of  pViilosoiDhy  is 
not  identical  with  the  problem  of  science  (although  it 
includes  it),  and  hence  the  methods  are  not  the  same.  It 
is  really  as  absurd  for  science  to  rail  at  philosophy, 
because  philosophy  in  a  sense  transforms  its  conclusions 
and  supersedes  its  categories,  as  it  would  be  for  "  common- 
sense  "  to  rail  at  science,  because  Si^cience  transforms  the 
notions  which  common-sense  is  accustomed  to  employ. 
Philosophy,  it  is  true,  does  not  stop  at  the  categories  of 
science,  but  neither  does  science  stop  at  the  crude  reality 
of  sense-perception.  We  can  easily  fancy  the  uncultured 
man  of  sense  sneering  at  the  scientist  as  a  dreamer,  because, 
forsooth,  he  declares  that  the  earth  moves  and  not  the  sun, 
or  because  he  asserts  the  rotundity  of  the  earth  and  the  exis- 
tence of  antipodes.  The  amount  of  transcendentalism,  in 
the  popular  sense  of  that  much-abused  word — if  by  it  be 
meant  distance  from  the  "  solid  ground  "  of  sense-percep- 
tion— in  the  higher  mathematics,  is  truly  something  ap- 
palling. In  a  sense,  the  conclusions  of  philosopliy  are  not 
real,  but  then  no  more  are  those  of  science.  Both  alike 
involve  a  departure  from  the  concrete  real  of  the  ordinary 
consciousness.  Each,  so  to  speak,  moves  in  a  world  of  its 
own,  which  (according  to  the  relative  perfection  attained 
in  the  formulation  of  the  respective  standpoints)  is  a 
world  more  or  less  perfectly  coherent  within  itself,  and 
with  the  standpoint  or  standpoints  which  fall  under  it  or 
which  it  embraces.  Science  at  once  embraces  and  tran- 
scends common-sense  in  the  higher  unity  which  consti- 
tutes scientific  truth;  philosophy  embraces,  while  it 
transcends  the  standpoints  alike  of  science  and  common- 
sense  in  the  ultimate  all-comprehensive  unity  which 
constitutes  philosophic  truth.  Hence,  as  it  has  been  justly 
said,  every  serious  philosophy,  that  is,  every  statement  of 
philosophic  truth  which  claims  to  be  even  approximately 
adequate,  must  include  materialism — materialism  being 
the  final  expression  of  an  interpretation  of  the  universe 
on  strictly  scientific  lines.     Any  statement  or  pretended 


S98  MODERN    PHILOSOPHY. 

statement  of  the  philosophic  position  v/hich  conflicts  with 
any  of  the  positive  doctrines  of  a  scientific  materialism  may 
therefore  be  without  hesitation  ignored.  "Philosophy," 
as  Professor  Seth  has  it,  "  is  ready,  accordingly,  to  accept 
and  patronise  any  theory  which  science  and  history  may 
establish.  Idealism  accepts  all  that  Physiology  has  to  say 
about  the  dependence  of  thought  on  the  organism,  and  is 
not  discomfited  by  the  most  materialistic  statements  of  the 
facts.  It  admits,  as  a  matter  of  course,  the  empirical  deri- 
vation of  all  our  conscious  life  from  feeling  or  sensation."* 
From  the  philosophical  standpoint  the  old  antagonisms 
and  controversies  lose  meaning,  or  at  least  their  nature  is 
entirely  changed ;  they  are  sublimated,  so  to  speak,  and 
reappear  in  a  higher  atmosphere.  Distinctions  which 
tinder  their  former  aspect  appeared  sharp,  clearly  de- 
finable and  irreconcilably  opposed,  now  resolve  themselves 
into  a  mere  question  of  emphasis.  Such,  as  we  take  it,  is 
the  case  with  Materialism  and  Idealism,  Theism  and 
Atheism,  &c.  A  formulation  of  the  philosophic,  interpre- 
tation of  the  world  which  shall  entirely  abolish  them 
remains  as  yet  a  desideratum;  but  from  even  a  more  or 
less  inadequate  statement  of  philosophic  theory,  such  as 
Hegeliani&;m,  all  their  former  importance  has  vanished  ; 
neither  side  is  confirmed  or  refuted,  but  they  are  deprived 
of  interest  in  proportion  as  their  opposition  tends  to 
become  insignificant. 

To  attain  to  a  complete  view  of  the  worhl,  such  is  the 
end  of  philosophy.  Science  rationalises  the  material 
furnished  by  common  experience ;  philosophy  rationalises 
the  material  furnished  by  science.  The  rationality  of 
either  is  not  the  coinage  of  our  brain,  but  a  part  of  the 
nature  of  things.  The  categories  of  science  are  real,  not- 
withstanding that  they  may  conflict  with  the  cruder 
notions  of  common-sense  ;  but,  viewed  from  the  standpoint 
of  common-sense,  they  are,  nevertheless,  ideal.  The  same 
with  philosophy;  its  categories  also  are  real  at  the  same  time 
that  they  are  ideal.     From  the  points  of  view  of  common- 

*  Of  course  it  remains  an  open  question  whether  current  statements 
of  the  HegeUan  position  do  not  have  a  formal  bias  wliich  in  effect 
gives  the  whole  an  anti-materialist  character.  This  question  has  been 
already  discussed. 


CONCLdSION.  3fl9 

sense  and  the  sci(,'ntific  intellect  respectively,  they  ore  ideal. 
Philosophy  .-ecs  an  n]tin)atu  identity  in  the  contradictions 
which  from  lower  planes  of  thought  are  irreconcilable  ;  it 
sees  idenlity  in  opposition,  being  in  becoming,  the  poten- 
tial in  the  actual,  the  matter  in  the  form.  These  distinc- 
tions are  only  maintained  as  aspects  of  a  whole,  and  their 
significance  as  opposites  consists  meiely  in  the  generic 
priority  or  jiosteriority  of  their  respective  momenta  as 
constitutive  of  the  essence  of  this  whole.  The  meaning 
of  the  history  of  philosophy  then  consists  in  its  being  an 
effort  of  the  human  mind  to  attain  a  view  of  this  Essence — 
Eeality— in  the  generic  order  of  its  deduction,  by  which 
alone  the  truo  meaning  of  the  synthesis  as  a  whole,  no  less 
than  that  of  the  elements  constituting  it,  is  discernible. 
There  is,  therefore,  as  we  said  before,  but  one  philosophy  as 
there  is  but  one  physical  science.  Metaphysic  like  Physic 
is  a  certain  way  of  envisaging  and  transforming  the  real 
world  of  .-ensible  experience.  Every  system  of  any  historical 
significance  has  differentiated  itself  from  other  systems  by 
emphasizing  some  point  or  aspect  which  the  rest  had 
neglected.  Its  defect  as  a  system  consists  in  its  having 
sought  to  give  exclusive  prominence  to  this  particular 
aspect  to  the  exclusion  of  others — m  its  endeavouring  to 
constitute  this  abstracted  element  a  whole  in  itself. 

By  the  inner  necessity  of  ]ts  own  nature  the  mind  is 
bound  to  pass  through  certain  successive  stages,  such  as 
dogmatism,  empiricism,  scepticism,  in  one  form  or  another 
before  it  is  in  a  position  to  grasp  the  properly  philosophic 
point  of  view.  It  is  what  we  may  term  a  part  of  the 
natural  freemasonry  of  things  that  the  mind  cannot  reach 
the  superior  without  having  previously  passed  over 
the  inferior  steps.  In  the  mysteries  of  the  ancient  reli- 
gious cults  during  the  earlier  stages  of  his  initiation,  the 
ultimate  doctrine  to  the  reception  of  which  those  stages 
were  preparatory,  was  carefully  hidden  from  the  neophyte. 
In  philosophy,  on  the  other  hand,  there  is  no  need  of 
artificial  concealment ;  the  whole  of  Hegel  may  be  an  open 
book  to  the  student,  so -far  as  paper  and  print  is  concerned, 
and  yet  it  will  be  absolutely  sealed  lore  to  him,  as  regards 
discovering  any  meaning  in  it,  if  he  have  not  passed 
through  the  preliminary  stages  of  his  speculative  initiation. 


400  MODEKN    PHILOSOPHY. 

In  the  first  blush  of  youth  the  mind  unhesitatingly  accepts 
all  things  in  their  immediateness,  be  it  "  common-sense," 
*'  morality,"  or  what-not.  The  period  of  reflection  follows, 
in  which  common-sense  and  naive  moral  sentiment  are 
negated  in  scepticism  and  cynicism ;  this  phase  of  thought, 
which  the  Germans  term  the  AufkJdrung,  is  followed  by 
another  which  consists  in  the  recognition  that  these  things 
are  not  entirely  empty  of  all  content  as  was  at  first  sup- 
posed, albeit  the  content  they  possess  is  entirely  different 
from  that  crudely  attributed  to  them  in  the  naive  stage  of 
innocence.''' 

Having  once  come  to  know  the  world  in  the  generic 
order  of  its  articulation  as  a  rational  whole,  we  are  iiTesis- 
tibly  driven  to  moot  the  problem  of  the  end,  purpose  or 
telos  of  this  world  ;  that  whither  it — and  a  fortiori  man,  the 
highest  product  up  to  date  of  natural  revolution — is  tend- 
ing. The  only  way  in  which  the  final  aim  or  ideal  of  pro- 
gress can  be  formulated  in  a  single  sentence,  is  that  it 
consists  in  the  realisation — the  bringing  to  consciousness 
of  the  world  in  its  full  meaning.  This  is,  of  course,  only 
another  way  of  repeating  that  the  end  of  progress  is  the 
actualization  of  the  immanent  pui  pose  of  the  world.  But  can 
we  discover  any  adequate  formula  for  this  absolute  world- 
telos  itself.  The  thinker  who  has  faced  the  problem  must 
unhesitatingly  answer  no.  We  may,  of  course,  make  use  of 
phrases  such  as  the  time-honoured  "  good  "  of  Plato,  but 
without  nearer  definition  tliey  must  remain  little  more 
than  j^hrases.  Turrhe]-,  we  are  bound  to  regard,  ex  hypothesis 
this  telos  as  absolute  finality,  while  we  are  conscious  of 

*  To  lake  an  illustration  of  this  hap-li:izaid ;  the  unsophisticated 
mind  never  doubts  the  existence  of  pure  disinterestedness  in  moral 
action;  a  follower  of  Helvetius  demonstrates  the  non-existence  of 
purely  disinterested  action,  the  unsophisticated  mind  resents  this 
demonstration  and  endeaxours  to  defend  its  orthodox  opinion,  but  in 
vain — the  cynic  triumphs  and  the  unsophisticated  mind  resigns  itself  to 
despair.  The  philosopher  at  last  appears,  and  proves  the  triumph  and 
despair  to  be  alike  irrational,  since  although  it  is  true  that  the 
bare  abstract  and  immediate  form  of  all  motive  whatever  is  self-interest, 
yet  that  this  does  not  in  any  way  atfect  the  fact  that  ilxa  content  of  the 
motive,  and  therefore  the  real  end  of  the  action,  may  be  wholly  without 
reference,  or  even  opposed  to  the  personal  interest  of  the  individual 
performing  the  action,  and  that  this  is  all  that  is  really  meant  when 
pure  disiutore^tedness  is  spoken  of. 


CONCLUSION.  401 

the  fact  that  finality  in  this  sense — a  being  in  which  there 
is  no  becoming,  a  form  with  no  material  content — involves 
an  abstraction,  and  therefore  no  longer  possesses  the  con- 
ditions of  a  real  synthesis. 

Let  ns  approach  the  problem  from  another  point  of 
view.  Cannot  we  regard  human  happiness,  it  may  be 
asked,  as  the  purpose  of  progress?  To  this  it  may  be 
answered  that  pleasure  or  happiness,  be  it  individual  or 
social,  can  never  be  an  end  in  itself,  although,  it 
is  true,  it  must  form  an  element  of  every  end,  where 
human  action  is  concerned.  It  is  a  triter  observation 
that  the  search  for  pleasure  qua  pleasure  invariably  defeats 
its  own  object.  Pleasure  or  happiness  is  consequent  on 
the  attainment  of  an  end  which  constitutes,  so  to  speak, 
the  substance  or  essence  of  which  pleasure  is  a  determina- 
tion. The  immediate  pursuit  of  pleasure,  therefore,  con- 
sidered as  an  end  in  itself,  is  the  pursuit  of  an  unreal 
abstraction.  The  desired  object,  end,  or  ideal  of  action 
is  hence,  we  repeat,  a  substance  or  essence  of  which  pleasure 
must  indeed  be  a  predicate,  but  which  is  primarily  pursued 
for  its  own  sake.  On  the  hypothesis  of  pleasure  per  se  ex- 
hausting the  whole  content  of  the  end  sought  after,  the 
ultimate  distinction  between  higher  and  lower  in  taste 
or  in  aim  remain  unaccounted  for ;  the  old  problem  of  the 
pig  happy  and  Sokrates  miserable,  in  spite  of  all  special 
pleading,  is  left  unresolved.  But  while  contending  thus 
far  against  the  view  of  Hedonism  as  commonly  formu- 
lated, we  must  not  forget  that  the  opposite  school  ignore 
the  fact  that  our  only  criterion  of  the  intrinsic  worth  of 
an  action  can  but  be  as  to  whether  it  conflicts  or  not  with 
the  free  development  of  ourselves  or  others,  or  of  society 
collectively ;  and  that  a  fortiori  the  highest  end  of  action 
consists  in  the  removal  of  the  impediments  in  the  way  of 
that  free  development — in  other  words,  in  that  which  tends 
to  the  greatest  possible  satisfaction  of  the  immediate  wants 
and  aspirations  of  all  men — which,  it  may  be  said,  is  only 
another  way  of  putting  the  hedonistic  criterion.  To 
argue  otherwise  is  to  revert  to  a  dogmatic  standpoint 
which  arbitrarily  fixes  the  purpose  of  Eeality.  The 
admission  that  hapjoiness  per  se  cannot  rationally  be 
conceived  as  constituting  the  telos  of  the  world-order  does 

2  D 


402  MODERN    PHILOSOPHY. 

not  preclude  tlie  conviction  that  it  is  logically  indissoluble 
from  it  ia  itself,  or  that  it  is  the  primary  condition  of  its 
realisation.  To  imagine  that  this  can  yield  to  any  a  priori 
assumption  as  to  what  tends  to  or  is  involved  in  the 
ultimate  realisation  of  the  world-pnrpose,  as  is  done  by 
the  late  Thomas  Hill  Green,  and  other  Neo-Hegelians  of 
his  school,  can  only  be  regarded  as  a  disastrous  attempt 
to  treat  a  purely  regulative  conception  as  con^titutive. 

The  endeavour  to  formulate  the  absolute  end  of  con- 
sciousness, or  the  immanent  purpose  of  the  world,  and 
to  make  this  the  basis  of  ethics,  is  tl:e  great  charac- 
teristic of  the  ethical  or  quasi-universal  religions.  These 
have  one  and  all  endeavoured,  so  to  speak,  to  strike  out  a 
short  cut  by  which  the  grand  denouement  might  be  placed 
within  reach  of  the  individual  soul.  Divers  are  the 
methods  in  the  various  creeds  by  which  perfection,  the 
perfect  good,  Nirvana,  union  with  God,  or  what-not,  is  to 
be  attained,  but  they  all  lie  in  the  severance  of  the  in- 
dividual from  nature  and  society  and  the  pleasures  of  the 
phenomenal  world,  in  the  destruction  of  his  natural 
appetites  and  aifections,  and  in  his  complete  withdrawal 
within  himself.  In  the  individual  sonl,  the  world-principle 
is  believed  to  realise  itself.  The  primal  impulse  toward 
regeneration  and  the  realisation  of  the  world-purpose  is 
hence  supposed  to  come  from  within.  The  consciousness 
is  now  awakening  in  men  that  there  is  no  short  cut 
to  perfection  or  to  the  Absolute,  whether  on  its  speculative 
side,  as  first  principle,  or  on  its  practical  side,  as  final  end 
of  the  world,  and  that  the  attempt  of  impatient  humanity 
to  make  one  is  an  illusion,  in  brief,  that  it  involves  an 
unreal  abstraction.  The  day  of  the  etliical  religions  is 
visibly  weaning,  and  one  can  only  view  with  regret  the 
futile  efforts  of  able  and  earnest  men  like  the  late  Professor 
Green,  who,  following  in  the  steps  of  Kant  and  the  post- 
Kantians,  would  stake  their  whole  intellectual  career  in 
the  forlorn  hope  of  resuscitating  the  "  ethics  of  inward- 
ness." With  the  decline  of  the  religions  of  introspective 
individualism,  the  significance  of  the  individual  as  such 
pales,  and  the  consciousness  grows,  that  only  in  and 
through  a  weary  course  of  social  development,  lies  the 
path  of  progress,  the  way  of  the  woi  Id-destiny.     Freedom, 


CONCLUSION.  403 

wliicli  im]ilies  the  satisfaction  of  existent  want  for  each  and 
for  all — first  and  foremost  the  animal  wants  the  intro- 
spectivist  disdains — is  the  first  condition  of  that  higher 
social  life  which  is  the  farthest  visible  summit  of  progress. 

This  consciousness  involves  a  radical  change  in  our 
ethical  and  religious  attitude.  Morality,  as  it  becomes 
political  and  social,  loses  its  exclusively  personal  character. 
»Sin  and  Holiness,  the  supreme  ethical  categories  of 
"  introspection,"  are  superseded  henceforth  in  reality  if 
not  in  name. 

The  attempt  to  formulate  the  telos  of  the  Eeal,  the  im- 
manent purpose  of  the  world,  is  surrendered  ;  much  more 
the  vain  etfort  to  reach  it  by  the  old  methods.  We 
expect  no  longer  to  attain  it  as  individuals  by  ecstasy, 
contemplation,  or  inward  illumination  :  "  Immer  holier  muss 
ich  streben,  Immer  weiter  mussich  schaun,"  may  still  be 
our  motto,  but  our  strivings  and  our  constant  looks  are 
directed  not  to  possible  heights  enshrouded  in  cloudland, 
but  to  the  limit  only  of  our  clear  and  distinct  vision.  We 
know,  at  all  events,  that  this  summit  must  be  reached, 
whatever  may  be  beyond,  before  that  beyond  can  become, 
in  its  turn,  a  distinct  ideal,  much  more  a  reality.  This 
point  of  view  in  its  own  way  demands  in  very  truth  the 
sacrifice,  the  negation,  of  the  individual,  but  it  is  not  as 
with  the  intro.s2:>ective  religions,  the  first  step  in  a  circular 
process  which  begins  with  the  natural  indivi^lual,  and 
ends  with  the  apotheosized  individual,  and  hence  which, 
its  primary  negation  of  the  individual  notwithstanding, 
remains  individualistic ;  but  a  negation  of  the  individual 
onl\'  in  so  far  as  this  is  essential  to  the  realisation  of 
that  higher  social  whole  into  which  he  enters.  In  short, 
the  abnegation  of  self  becomes  on  this  view  a  mere 
accident  of  morality,  and  not,  as  before,  a  part  of  its 
substance. 

"  Philosophy,"  says  Hegel,  "deals  only  with  the  universal 
individual ;  "  the  general  form  of  individuation  or  person- 
ality may  be  deducible,  but  not  the  concrete  personality 
determined  in  a  specific  time-content.  "  The  individual 
in  this  sense,"  as  Fichte  has  well  said,  "belongs  to  the 
element  of  the  purely  contingent ;  "  and  we  would  add  its 
meaning,  its  reality,  is  to  be  found  in  so-iety;  for  society 


404  MODERN   PHILOSOPHY. 

represents  the  highest  actual  realisation  of  the  world 
principle,  by  whatever  name  we  call  it,  "  nenn's  Gliick, 
Herz,  Liebe,  Gott."  There  is  nothing  above  or  beyond 
society.  Society  or  humanity  stands  for  that  universal 
personality  which  is  permanent  and  abiding  in  the  tiux  of 
the  particular,  the  individuals,  constituting  it.  Whether 
this  larger  life  manifesting  itself  on  the  plane  of  history 
as  for-itself  in  the  individual  subjectivities,  which  are  its 
evanescent  components,  is  destined  to  attain  to  in-and- 
for-itse\fness  in  the  time  order,  in  other  words,  to  be  its 
own  subject,  is  a  question  which  ever  and  anon  recurs  to 
0]ie,  more  especially  when  one  reflects  on  the  ruthlessness 
with  which  historic  evolution  sacrifices  the  individual 
man  on  the  altar  of  progress,  and  above  all  when  one 
feels  that  the  noblest  type  of  individual  character  is 
that  which  is  prepared  for  this  sacrifice  when  the  occasion 
firises.  Such  a  speculation,  if  we  like  to  entertain  it,  is 
as  worthy  as  any  which  conceives  of  a  perpetuity  of 
individual  existence  as  such. 

A  word  may  be  expected  in  conclusion,  as  to  the 
immediate  future  and  prospects  of  philosophy.  Since  the 
death  of  Hegel  there  has  been  no  great  original  philo- 
sophic genius,  no  thinker  who  has  thrown  any  essentially 
new  light  on  the  ultimate  problem  of  philosophy.  Dog- 
matic Pessimism,  that  product  of  effete  civilization,  has 
had  a  passing  success.  Great  scientific  generalizers  like 
Herbert  Spencer  have  formulated  the  ultimate  princij^les 
of  Cosmology,  in  the  light  of  the  two  great  scientific 
achievements  of  the  age,  the  doctrines  of  the  "  Persistence 
of  force  "  and  of  "  Evolution."  But,  save  for  the  recent 
academic  movements  of  Neu-Hegelianism,  there  is  little 
noteworthy  to  record.  The  immediate  future  of  philo- 
sophy, the  next  foi  mulation  of  the  ultimate  world- problem 
of  being  and  knowledge,  which  Nhall  appeal  to  the  think- 
ing portion  of  mankind,  to  a  greater  extent  than  even 
Plato,  Aristotle,  or  Hegel  ever  did,  must,  we  believe,  be 
sequent  on  the  realisation  of  that  vast  transformation  with 
which  the  current  order  of  things  is  big.  "  The  republic 
has  no  need  of  chemists,"  Lavoisier  was  told.  Thus  with 
brutal  frankness  was  the  truth  expressed,  that  in  periods 


CONCLUSION.  405 

of  g;reat  political  and  social  change,  Theory,  as  such, 
be  it  .scientific  or  philosophical,  must  cede  to  the  all- 
absorbing  questions  of  Practice.  The  stud(3nt  as  he  lays 
down  this  little  volume,  should  he  by  chance  take  up  a 
newspaper,  will  inevitabl}?-  light  on  accounts  of  great 
strikes,  of  armaments,  of  the  struggle  for  colonics  called 
imperial  expansion,  of  vast  popular  revolutionary  move- 
ments, etc.,  all  of  which  point  to  one  thing,  when  followed 
out  in  all  their,  bearings,  the  steady  approach  of  the 
great  class  struggle.  Let  him  ponder  on  this  and  bethink 
himself  of  the  part  even  he,  or  if  not  he,  his  children,  may 
be  forced  to  take  in  the  resolution  of  that  great  living 
contradiction — the  contradiction  between  individual  and 
society — expressed  in  what  we  term  Modern  Civilization. 


INDEX. 


Note. — The  names  of  philosophical  works  are  printed  in  italics. 


Abelard,  116;  his  doctrine,  117 

Abstract-Dogmatic  systems  of 
modern  philosophy,  144 ;  reac- 
tion against  scholasticism,  144; 
Descartes,  146 ;  Malebranche, 
155 ;  Spinoza,  157 ;  Leibnitz, 
167;  Wolff,  175;  Baumgarten, 
175 ;  Crusius,  176 

Aim  Baker,  121 

Academics,  the,  77 

Achilles-puzzie  to  prove  the  im- 
possibility of  motion,  34 

Adamson,  Kobert,  390 

j!Ene>idemus,  86 

Esthetic,  Aristotle's,  74;  Her- 
l^art's,  308  ;  Hegel's  lectures  on, 
332 

Airrippa  Saturninns,  86 

Albertus  Magnus,  124 

Albigensianism,  102 

Alchemists  and  cosmic  speculators 
of  the  sixteenth  century,  137 ; 
the  epoch  of  the  "occult  sciences," 
138 ;  Eeuchlin,  138  ;  Agrippa, 
von  Netteslieim,  138 ;  Paracelsus, 
139 ;  Card  anus.  142 ;  authorities, 
143 

Alexander  the  Great  a  pupil  of 
Aristotle,  66 

Alexandria,  the  seat  ctf  Neo-Plato- 
nism,  89 

Alexandrian  Gnostics,  the,  100; 
Basilides,  100  ;  Karpokrates,  100 ; 
Talentinus,  100  ;  doctrines,  101 

Alexandrian  trinity,  the,  94 

A'farabi.  120 


Al  Ghazzali,  121 

Alkendi,  119 

Ammonius   Saccas,  92 ;  reputed  a 

Christian,  107 
Annxao;ora8,  life,  39 ;   philosophy, 

39,  68  ;  teacher  of  Sokrates,  44 
Anaximandros,  24,  68  ;  inventions, 

25  ;  speculations   on  the  primal 

substance,  25  ;  on  evolution,  25 
Anaximenes,  life,  26;  doctrines,  27 
Anselm,     114;      his      philosophy 

subservient    to     theology,    114; 

doctrines,     114 ;     dispute    with 

Roscellinus,  115 
Antinomies  of  the  pure  reason,  244 
Antiochus  of  Askalon,  77 
Antisthenes,  49;  founds  the  Cynic 

school,  49 ;  virtue  to  be  attained 

by  asceticism,  49 
Anytos,  46 
Apocrypha,    tendency    to     Greek 

thought  in  the,  89 
Apollodorus,  82 
Apollonius  of  Tyana,  88 
Aquinas,    Thomas,    125;   his   doc- 

trinep,     125 ;     two     sources    of 

knowledge,   125;    hid   influence 

on  later  thought,  126 
Arabian    philosophers,     119;     Al- 
kendi, 119;  Alfarabi,  120;  Avi- 

cennn,  120;    Al    Ghaz/ali,   121; 

Abu  Beker,  121 ;  Averroes,  121 
Aristippus,    48 ;    founds    Cyrenaic 

school,  48 ;  writings  lost,  49 
Aristophanes,    ignorant    satire   of 

phih'sophy,  44 


INDEX. 


407 


Aristotle,  birtli  nnd  education,  65 ; 
tutor  to  Alexander  the  Great, 
G() ;  led  uring  and  death,  66 ; 
early  writinsjs,  66 

Aristotle's  philosophy,  definition 
of  philosophy,  3,  67 ;  his  doc- 
triues  not  derived  from  Sokrates, 
21 ;  his  school  complementary, 
not  opposed,  to  that  of  Plato,  51 ; 
Aristotle  the  founder  of  the  in- 
ductive method  and  of  natural 
science,  53 ;  editions  of  his 
writings,  67 ;  division  of  philo- 
sophy into  logic,  physics,  and 
ethics,  67 ;  what  is  a  principle  ? 
67 ;  on  matter  and  form,  68 ;  on 
efficient  and  final  causes,  69,  70 ; 
on  reality,  69 ;  cosmologii-al  ar- 
gument, 71 ;  on  Nature,  71  ; 
happiness  the  goal  of  human  j 
activity,  72 ;  virtues,  73 ;  the  [ 
Politics,  73  ;  art-philosophv,  74  ;  j 
theory  of  formal  logic,  75 ;  the 
range  of  his  writings,  75 ;  bib- 
liography, 76;  referred  to,  60, 
91,  112,  117,  120,  124,  396 

Aj-istoxenus,  77 

Arius,  heresy  of,  107 

Arkesilaus,  77 

Art,  a  quietude  of  the  will,  298  ; 
the  chief  periods  of,  and  their 
characteristics,  Hegel  on,  332 ; 
the  progress  of,  Hegel  on,  333 

Art,  philofeophv  of,  Aristotle's,  74  ; 
Schelling's,  283,  286 

Athanasius,  107 

Athenagoras,  104 

Afomists,  philcsophical  system  of 
the,  40;  nature  and  action  of 
atoms,  41 ;  explanation  of  per- 
ception, 41 

Atoms,  nature  and  action  of,  41 

Augustine  of  Hippo,  108 ;  his  be- 
lief, 108;  his  Platonism,  108; 
his  orthodoxy  only  apparent,  109 

Aurelius,  IVlarcus,  80,  87 

Autliorities   for.  Oriental  thought, 

20  ;  Greek  philosophy,  23  ;  Hera- 

kleitos,  38  ;  Plato  and  Aristotle, 

I     76;  the  Stoics  and  Epicm-eans, 

I 


84 ;  the  Gnostics  and  Christian 
Fatliers,  110;  tlie  philosophy  of 
the  Middle  Ages,  130;  the  Ger- 
ma-i  jNIystics,  131 ;  the  sixteenth 
century  speculators,  143 ;  Spinoza, 
167 

Averrocs,  121 

Avicebron,  123 

Avicenna,  120 

Baadee,  F.,  von,  287 

Bacon,  Francis,  177;  founder  of 
the  Empiricist  movement,  177; 
survey  of  knowledge,  178 ;  philo- 
sophy, 178,  215 

Bain,  Alexander,  and  his  works, 
378 

Bardesanes,  101 

Bardili,  254 

Basilides,  100 

Bauer,  Bruno,  338,  340 

Bauer,  Edgar,  340 

Baumgarten,  Alexander  Gottlieb, 
175 

Baur;  Ferdinand  Christian,  339 

Bayle,  Didionnaire,  10 

Beattie,  James,  203 

Beck,  254 

Bekker,  Balthasar,  155 

Berkeley,  George,  188;  account  of 
his  work,  188,  216;  no  universal 
idea,  189;  what  we  mean  by 
"  material  substance,"  189  ;  con- 
clusion from  Ilia  analysis,  191 ; 
his  aim  and  writings,  192  ;  works, 
193 

Blakey,  Robert,  histoiy  of  philo- 
sophy, 13 

Boehme,  Jacob,  286 

Boethius,  96 

"  Bombastic,"'  origin  of  the  word, 
140 

Bonnet,  Charles,  204  ;  works,  205 

Brown,  Thomas,  203 

Brucker,  Johann  Jacob,  history  of 
philosophy,  10, 13 

Bruno,  Giordano,  134,  137;  wan- 
derings, 134;  death,  135;  philo- 
sopliy,  185 

Buddha,  98 


408 


INDEX. 


Buhle,  J.  G.,  history  of  plnlosopliy, 

11 
Burdach,  287 

Cabanis,  213 

Caird,  Edward,  390,  391.  392 

Canijianella,  Thomas,  137 

Cardamis,  Hieronymus,  and  his 
works,  142 

Carvaka,  school  of,  119 

Causality,  Schopenhauer's  four 
forms  of  the  principle  of,  290 

Causation,  Hume's  theory  of,  196 

Champeaux,  William  of,  116 

Chosroes,  96 

Christ,  Gnostic  idea  of  the,  101 

Christian  Dogmatics  in  their  De- 
velopment, Strauss's,  339 

Christian  trinity  distinguished  from 
the  Neo-Platonic,  9-4 

Christianity ;  influence  of  Neo- 
Platonism  on,  92;  of  the  sixth 
century,  97  ;  the  anti-worldliness 
of,  98 :  the  reason  of  its  supre- 
macy, 99  ;  its  dogmas  formulated 
by  Athauasius,  107 ;  at  Nicaea, 
107 

Chrysippus,  79,  80 

Cicero  and  his  philosophical  works, 
87 

Claude,  213 

Clement  of  Alexandria,  104 

Common  sense,  attached  by  Plato, 
55  ;  recognised  by  Aristotle,  67 

Comte,  Auguste,  definition  of  philo- 
sophy, 4  ;  life,  364,  374  ;  parallel 
between  the  doctrines  of  Comte 
and  Hegel,  365 ;  the  Positive 
Fhilosopliy,  367 ;  Comte's  law  of 
the  three  stages  ot  philosophy, 
367 ;  Sociology  the  goal  of  all 
sciences,  368  ;  arrangement  of  the 
sciences,  368 :  Comte's  view  of 
historic  evolution,  369  ;  his 
scheme  of  social  reconstruction, 
372 ;  Sociology  not  founded  by 
Comte,  373  ;  the  real  advance  he 
made,  374 ;  his  defective  charac- 
ter, 374 ;  revered  by  his  followers, 
375  ;  natm-e  of  positivism,  376 


Condillac,  Etieime  Bonnot  de.  203  ; 

works,  203;  Sensationism,  204 
Cosmological  argument  of  Aristotle, 

71 
Cosmology     of    the     Pythagorean 

system,  32  ;  of  Aristotle,  71 ;  of 

Paracelsus,  140 
Cousin,   Victor,    history   of    philo- 
sophy, 13 
Critique  of  Practical  Reason,  Kant's, 

225,  248 
Critique   of  Pure   Reason,  Kant's, 

217,  2:^3,  224,  234,  236,  238,  241, 

244,  247 
Critique  of  the  Faculty  of  Judgment. 

Kanfs,  225,  252 
Cromaziano,  history  of  philosophy, 

11 
Crusius,  Christian  August,  176 
Cynic  School,  49 ;  origin  of  the  name, 

49  ;  its  sole  end  the  avoidance  of 

pleasure,  49 
Cyrenaic  Scliool,  48 

Damascits,  96 

De  anima,  Aristotle's,  72 

Degerando,  history  of  philosophy,  13 

Demiurge,  the,  61,  101 

Demokritos,  40 ;  founder  of  the 
Atomistic  system,  40 

Descartes,  Ke'ne,  and  his  works, 
146 ;  doctrines,  147 ;  character, 
154 

Descartes'  philosophy,  147  :  '  Me- 
thodic Doubt,'  147;  the  existence 
of  self,  147,  214;  of  God,  149; 
canon  of  investigation,  149,  214; 
independent  conceptions,  150  ; 
Descartes'  dualism,  151  ;  his 
physics,  151 ;  physical  theories, 
152 ;  psychology,  152 ;  anthro- 
pology, 153  ;  influence  of  his 
doctrines,  155 ;  referred  to,  156, 
159,  170,  186,  214 

Deslandes,  hi.^tory  of  philosophy,  10 

Dialectic,  the  Hegelian,  313;  use 
of  the  term,  324 

Diderot,  Denis,  life,  206  ;  works, 
207 ;  materialism,  207  ;  method, 
210 


INDEX. 


409 


Dikoarchus,  77 

Dioirenes  Laertius,  history  of  philo- 
sophy, 10 

piogenes  of  Apolloiiia,  birthpLice, 
27 ;  phHosophy,  ^7 ;  the  fiivt  to 
stiite  the  principle  of  Monism, 
28,  /)1 

piogenes  of  Sinope,  50 

Diogenes  the  Stoic,  80 

Diihring,  Eugen,  history  of  philo- 
sophy, lii;  dootrin<-s.  861 

Duns  Scotiis,  127 ;  writings,  127  ; 
doctrine,  128 

ECKHART,  131 

Ego,  activity  of  the,  260 

Eidology,  3("!6 

Eloatic  school.  33 :  XenOi/Iianes, 
33  ;  Parmeuide.-i,  33 ;  Meliosos  and 
Zeno,  34 

Emotions,  Hume's  classification  of 
the,  199 

Empedokles,  birth,  38 ;  doctrine  of 
four  elements,  and  uniting  and 
separating  principles,  38,  68 ;  ex- 
planation of  Sense  perception, 
38 

ETupirical-Sceptical  schools  of  mo- 
dern philosophv,  177 ;  Baci^n, 
177;  Hobbes,  180;  Locke,  182; 
Berkeley,  188;  Hiune,  193; 
Raid,  201 

Encyclopedie^  the.  207 

EncyUofiddie,  &c.,  Hegel's,  325, 327, 
328,  349 

Enfield,  condensation  of  Brucker's 
history,  11,  13 

En  gels,  Friedrich,  341 

Fvtretien  evire  D'Alemhert  et 
Diderot,  Diderot's,  207,  208,  210 

Ej.ictftus,  80,  87 

Epicureans,  doctrines  of  the,  81 ; 
their  kanonik,  81 ;  pbysics,  81 ; 
ethif^s,  81 ;  their  doctrines  not 
original,  82 

Efticurus,  definition  of  philosophy, 
3,  67 ;  life.  80 

Epiphanes,  103 

Erdmann,  J.  E,,  history  of  philo- 
sophy, 12,  314 


Erigena,  Jolinnnes  Scotus,  111, 
doctrines,  112 

E;<enbeck.  von,  287 

Essay  on  ilw  Iliciuan  Understanding, 
Locke's,  182.  187 

Essenes,  the,  90 

Ethics,  Ari>tntle's,  73  :  Spinoza's, 
l.nS,  159,  160.  1(52,  163.  106,  167 

Euklid  of  Megaru,  48  ;  founds 
Megcirie  school,  48  ;  writings 
lost,  49 

Evolution,  anticipation  of,  by 
Anaximandros,  26 ;  Hegel's  error 
concerning,  327;  Spencer's  defi- 
nition of,  384  ;  principles  of,  885  ; 
tendency  towards  equilibration, 
387 

Experience,  nature  of,  67,  196 ;  all 
knowledge  derived  from,  183 ; 
how  possible,  226 

Fathers,  tbe  Christian,  103;  the 
philosophic  Fathers,  103;  Justin 
Martyr,  103;  Athenagoras,  104; 
Theo'philus,  104;  Irenajus,  104; 
Hippolytus,  104 ;  Minucius  Felix, 
104;  clement  of  Alexandria,  104  ; 
Oiiiien,  105  ;  the  dogmatic 
Fi.thers,  106;  Athanasius,  107; 
Augustine  of  Hippo,  108 ;  autho- 
rities, 110 

Favorinus,  86 

FeiTier,  377 

Feuerback,  Ludwig  Andreas,  341 

Fichte,  Johann  Gottlieb,  life,  256 ; 
works,  257 

Fichte's  philosophy.  258  ;  '  Theory 
of  Knowledge,'  258  ;  the  task  of 
philosophy,  258  ;  fundamental 
axiom  of  the  Theory  of  Know- 
ledge, 259  ;  second  axiom,  261 ; 
third  axiom,  261 ;  division  of  the 
Theory  of  Knowledge  into  specu- 
lative and  practical,  262 ;  '  Specu- 
lative Theory  of  Knowledge,* 
263 ;  standpoint  and  system  of 
the  '  Theory  of  Science,'  263  ;  its 
method,  266;  'Practical  Tiieory 
of  Knowledge,'  2(i7 ;  liow  the  Ego 
comes    to   ascribe    causality    to 


410 


INDEX. 


itself,  267 ;  freedom  of  the  indi- 
vidual, 270  ;  aniicipations  of 
Socialism,  271 ;  Fichte's  ethics, 
271 ;  the  fallacy  of  the  intro- 
spective ethics  as  a  basis  for 
conduct,  275;  opposition  to 
Fichte's  philosophy,  277 ;  retro- 
spect and  criticism,  317 ;  referred 
to,  278,  280,  282,  284,  286,  287, 
300,  319,  347,  403 

Ficinus,  Marsilius,  133 

Figulus,  Nigidius,  88 

First  Principles,  Spencer's,  381,  382, 

■    383,  38(5,  388 

Fischer,  Kuuo,  344 

Force,  Principle  of  the  pers^istence 
of,  and  its  consequences,  382 

Form,  as  understood  by  Aristotle, 
68 

Fouille'c,  Alfred,  history  of  philo- 
sophy, 13 

Foundation  for  the  Metaphysic  of 
Ethic,  Kant's,  225,  248 

Fourfold  root  of  the  principle  of 
adequate  cause,  Schopenhauer's, 
289,  290 

Frauensfadt,  301 

Free-wilL,  upheld  by  Aristotle,  73 ; 
admitted  by  Leibnitz,  173  ;  Hmne 
on,  196;  d'Hulbach  on,  212; 
Herbart  on,  309 

French  materialist  school,  203 ; 
Condillac,  2iJ3  :  Bonnet,  204  ; 
Helvetius,  205  ;  La  Mettrie,  206 ; 
Diderot,  206;  d'Holbach,  211 

Fries,  254 

Gadants,  77 

Gans,  338 

German  mysticism  of  fourteenth 
and  fifteenth  centuries,  130 ; 
Eckhart,  131 ;  Tauler,  131 ;  'A 
German  theology,'  131 ;  autho- 
rities, 131 

Gersonides,  124 

Gnosticism,  100:  origin  and  pro- 
gress, 100;  Alexandrian  Gnostics, 
100;  Syrian  Gnostics,  101;  doc- 
trines, 101 ;  idea  of  the  Christ, 
101 ;  refuted  by  Irenaeus,  104 


God,  Descartes'  argument  for  the 
existence  of,  149;  the  God  of 
Leibnitz,  171 

Gorgias,  42,  49 

Gorgias,  Plato's,  56 

Goschel,  338 

Greek  philosophy,  periods  of,  21  ; 
authorities,  23;  I.  Pre-Sokratic 
Schools,    23;    IL    Sokrates,  44; 

III.  Plato    and   Aristotle,   51; 

IV.  Academies  and  Peripatetics, 
Stoics,  Epicureans  and  Sceptics, 
77 ;  V.  Roman  and  Antiquarian 
period,  85 ;  VI.  Neo-Platonism, 
89 

Green,  T.  H.,  390,  392 
Gwinner,  Dr.,  301 

Haldane,  J.  S.,  390 

Haldane,  E.  B.,  390 

Hamann's  opposition  to  Kant's 
philosophy,  253 

Hamilton,  Sir  William,  377,  378 

Hartenstein,  310 

Hartmann,  EdAvard  von,  352;  his, 
philosophy,  352 ;  reconcilhig  the 
doctiines  of  Hegel  and  i^chopen- 
hauc,  „_:■;  conjunction  of  will 
and  intelligence,  353 ;  the  happi- 
ness of  the  conscious  individual, 
not  the  purpose  of  the  world, 
355 ;  the  possibility  of  realising 
this  happines;>  an  illusion,  355 ; 
defects  of  Hartmann's  system, 
357 

Hebrew  prophets,  the,  and  the 
"  gospel  of  inwardness,"  98 

Hegel,  Georg  Wilhelm  Friedrich, 
life,  310 ;  work  with  Schelling, 
311 ;  works,  311 

Hegelian  school,  the,  338 

Hegelian  system,  the,  definition 
of  philosophy,  4 ;  the  ultimate 
princif  >le  of  knowledge,  312 ;  dia- 
lectical method  of  Hegel,  313; 
basis  of  the  Hegelian  dialectic, 
315;  the  progress  of  knowledge 
sliown,  317 ;  stages  which  the 
mind  and  humanity  pass  through 
before  attaining  absolute  know- 


INDEX.  411 


Icrlge,   319;    extracts  from   the 
'Phenomenology'  in  illustration 
of  Hegel's  style,  310  ;  his  logic, 
322 ;    its   throe    main    divisions, 
323;    use  of  the  word  dialectic, 
324 ;  first  division  of  logic,  the 
doctrine  of   being,  325 ;   second 
division,  the  doctrine  of  essence, 
325  ;  third  division,  the  doctrine 
of  concept,  32G ;  correspondence 
of  these   divisions  with  Kant's, 
326;    Kegels  philosophy  of  na- 
ture, 327 ;   his  error  concerning 
evolution,   327;    his   division  of 
the  philosophy  of  nature,   327  ; 
on  the  death  of  the  individual, 
328 ;    his   philosophy    of  mind, 
329  ;  its  triple  division,  329  ;  his 
ethic,     329 ;      lectures     on    the 
philosophy  of  history,  330 ;  Erd- 
mann's    opinion   of    them,   332 ; 
lectures   on   aesthetic,  332 ;    the 
chief  periods   of    art  and   their 
characteristics,  332  ;  progress  of 
art,  333;    Hegel's    view   of  the 
significance    of    art,   334 ;    phi- 
losophy of  religion,    334 ;    har- 
monisation  between   his  system 
I  and  the  Prntestant  Christianity 
I  of  Prussia,  334,  337, 339  ;  history 
of  philosophy,  12,  335  ;  collapse 
!  of  Htgelianism  as  a  school,  336  ; 
I  its  success  as  a  distinct  system, 
I  337  ;  controversies  after  Hegel's 
'  death,  338 ;  retrospect  and  criti- 
cism, 348 ;  referred  to,  288,  300, 
347,  352,  365,  396,  403 
leinrichs,  338 
leloise,  116 

lelvetius,  Claude  Adrien,  165, 205; 
I  doctrines,  205 

lerakleitos,     life,    36  ;      cardinal 
I  doctrine  of  eternal  fiux  of  things, 

36,  52 
leraklides  of  Pontus,  77 
lerbart,  Johann  Friedrich,  301 
lerbart's  philosophy  :  definition  of 
philosophy,   4  ;    position   of  his 
philosophy,    288 ;     influence    of 
Kantism  on  it,  302,  303  ;  results 


furnished  by  logic,  302 ;  two 
cliisses  of  conceptions,  302;  re- 
lation of  physics  and  metaphysics, 
303;  division  of  metaphysics, 
304 ;  general  metaphysics,  in- 
cluding logic  and  ontology,  304  ; 
applied  metaphysics,  305 ;  syne- 
chology,  305 ;  eidology,  306 ; 
psychology,  307 ;  aesthetics,  308 ; 
tlieory  of  religion,  309  ;  theory 
of  pedagogic,  309  ;  politics,  309  ; 
success  of  Herbart's  doctrines  due 
to  their  matiiematical  dress,  309 ; 
retrospect  and  criticit<m,  348 

Herder,  J.  G.,  opposition  to  Kant's 
philosophy,  253 

Hereditary  genius,  Aristotle,  an 
example  of,  66 

Hermarchus,  82 

Hermes  Trismegistus,  90 

Hermodorus,  77 

Herrennius,  107 

Hippias,  43 

Hippo,  27 

Hippolytus,  104 

History  of  pliilosophy,  objection 
to  a  condensed  history,  8  ;  need 
of  such  a  history,  9 ;  three  plans 
of  writing  a  history  of  philosophy, 
9  ;  ancient  and  modern  histories, 
10 ;  Hegel's,  335 

History,  philosophy  of,  first  hinted 
at  by  Cardanus,  143 ;  Kant's 
views  on,  250  ;  Hegel's,  330 

Hobbes,  Thomas,  180 ;  definition  of 
philosophy,  180  ;  experience  and 
observation,  the  source  of  know- 
ledge, 180;  doctrine,  180,  215; 
theorv  of  society,  182 

Holbach,  Baron  d',  liff,  211 ;  the 
iSysteme  de  la  Naiure,2\\',  ma- 
terialism, 211 ;  conception  of 
God,  212;  free-will,  212;  in- 
fluence of  materialism  on  conduct, 
212 

Hume,  David,  193;  works,  193; 
position  in  the  history  of  phi- 
losophy, 194 ;  impressions  and 
ideas,  194 ;  nature  of  experience, 
196,  216  ;  free-will,  196;  doctrine 


412 


INDEX. 


of  the  soul-substance,  197 ;    in- 
quiry into  the  basis  of  morals,  199 
Hypatia,  95 

Idea,  the  highest,  to  which  all 
others  tend,  58 

Ideal  of  the  pure  reason,  247 

Ideas,  as  understood  by  Plato,  58 ; 
Descartes'  classification  of,  153 ; 
not  innate,  183;  of  sensation  and 
of  relation,  184;  enumeration  nf, 
184 ;  combination  of,  185,  204 ; 
all  ideas  only  states  of  tiie  mind, 
189;  Hume's  dir,tinction  between 
impressions  and  ideas,  194;  ideas, 
as  understood  by  Kant,  241 

Ideas,  ultimate  scientific,  381. 

Ideas  for  a  Universal  History,  &c., 
Kant's,  250 

Ideas  of  pure  reason,  243 

Identity,  Scliellinjij's  system  of,  278 

Indiviihial  and  his  Property,  Max 
Stiraer's,  342 

Induction,  Aristotle's,  condemned 
by  Bacon,  179 

Inductive  method,  foundation  of, 
45  ;  Aristotle  the  true  founder,  53 

Inquiry  concerning  Human  Under- 
standing, Hume's,  193 

Instauration  of  the  Sciences,  Bacon's, 
178 

Interpretation  delanature,DideToV  a, 
207,  208 

Ionian  schools  of  philosophy,  22, 
6S;  theirprobleras,22,51;  Thales, 
23 ;  Anaximandros,  24  ;  Aiiaxi- 
menes,  26 ;  Diogeues  of  Apol- 
lonia,  27 

Irenaeus,  104 

Isidore,  96 

Italian  school  of  philosophy,  29 ; 
Pvthagoras,  29 ;  Pytiiagorean 
System,  30 

Jacobi,  F.  H.,  opposition  to  Kant's 
philosophy,  254 ;  to  Fichte's,  277 

Jamblichos,  94,  95 

Jena  Allgemeine  Literatur  Zeitung, 
the,  on  Kant's  '  Criticism,'  252 

Jewish  philosophers,  122 ;  doctrine 


of  the  Kabbala,  122;  Avicebron 

123 ;  Mainionides,  123 
Ju-tin  Martyr,  103 
Justinian,  the  Neo-Platonic  school. 

closed  by,  96 

Kabbala,    doctrine    of   the,    122  ■ 
study  of,  138 

Kanonik,  the,  of  the  Epicureans 
81 

Kant  and  the  Post-Kan tians.  school 
of,  214;  Kant.  224;  Fichte.  256 
Schelling,  278 ;  Schopenhauer 
289;  Herbal  t,  301  ;  Hegel,  310 
the  Heg.'lian  school,  338 ;  on  th( 
development  from  Kant  to  Hegel , 
345 

K'Hnt,  Immanuel,  life,  224;  works 
224 ;  editions  of  his  works,  225 
his  greatness,  256 

Kant's  philosophy :  definition  o 
philosophy,  4;  outline  of  hi- 
l^hilosophy,  217;  '  The  Critica 
doctrine,'  225  ;  how  is  experienc( 
possible  ?  226  ;  disadvantage  un 
der  which  Kant  worked,  226 
'Transcendental  Esthetic,'  229 
meaning  of  '  Transcendental, 
229;  inquiry  into  the  transcen 
dental  conditions  of  sensibility 
229 ;  '  Transcendental  Analytic, 
231 ;  the  function  of  the  under 
standing,  232  ;  logical  table  o 
judgments,  232 ;  transcendenta 
table  of  the  conceptions  of  thi 
understanding,  233 ;  deductioi 
of  the  categories  from  a  primary 
principle  of  consciousness,  233 
'  Transcendental  Dialectic,'  241 
ideas,  241 ;  distinction  betweei 
the  understanding  and  th( 
reason,  242 ;  ideas  of  pur( 
reason,  243  ;  paralogisms,  243 
antinomies,  244 ;  ideal  of  pure 
reason,  247 ;  Kant's  moral  phi 
losophy,  248;  metaphysic  o 
ethics,  250 ;  philosophy  of  his 
tory,  250 ;  the  goal  of  history 
250  ;  Critique  of  the  Faculty  o 
Judgment,  252;  reception  of  th< 


INDEX. 


413 


,12: 


tibrij  criHcal   pliilosophy,    252;   early- 
writers     on     Kantianism,    253 ; 
opposition  to  Kant's  doctrines,  of 
Uamann,  253;    of  Herder,  253; 
of  Jacobi,  254  ;    the  position  of 
Criticism '    as    a   system,  255 ; 
the  transcendental  method  Kants 
great  heritage,   256;    retrospect 
and  criticism,  345,  347  ;  referred 
to,  167,  186,  217,  260,  262,  263, 
266,  269,  283,  286,  287,  290,  291, 
302,  314,  326,  345,  347 
Ijarneades,  77 
arpokrates,  100 
enite;^,  the,  102 

jf(   erinthus,  100 
'    leanthes,  80 

fo,   lein,  G.  M.,  287 

25   rates,  78 

ratylos,  Plato'^,  57 
rause,  K.  C.  F.,  287 
ritias,  46 

A    Mettrie,  Julien    Offroy    de, 

206 

iaforet,  history  of  philosophy,  13 
ange,     Friedrich     Albert,    362 ; 

History  of  Materialism,  12,  362  ; 

first    part,    Materialism     before 

Kant,  362  ;  second  part,  Modern 

Materialism,  363 
ao-tse,  16 
laws,  Plato's,  64 
<eheti  Jesu,  Strauss's,  339 
eibnitz,  Gottfried  Wilhelm,  167 ; 

studies,  168 

i^eibuitz's    philosophy,    168,   215; 
I  monads,  168,  172;  their  changes, 
I  169  ;     unconscious      perception, 
169  :  proirression  among  monads, 
170  ;  distinction  between  emjiiri- 
cal  and  necessary  truth,  171 ;  God, 
171 ;  inconsistencies  on  his  sys- 
tem,  173;    freedom   of  the   will 
admitted,  173;  his   system   con- 
trasted   with    that    of   Spinoza, 
174  ;  its  influence,  174 
eukippus,  40 
eviathan,  Hobbes',  180 
iCwes,   George   Henry,  hifctory  of 


philosophy,  13;  work,  379; 
Problems  of  Life  and  Mind,  379  ; 
the  aim  of  philosophy,  380 ; 
result  of  his  work,  380 

Locke,  John,  182;  account  of  his 
philosophy,  183;  ideas  not  innate, 
183,  216;  ideas  of  sensation  and 
reflection,  183 :  enumeration  of 
ideas,  184;  substances,  185;  know- 
ledge, 186;  division  of  know- 
ledge, 187;  influence  of  his 
writings,  187 

Logic,  Aristotle's  theory  of  formal, 
75 ;  logic  of  the  Stoics,  78 ;  or  the 
Epicureans,  81 ;  the  Port-Royal 
logic,  155 ;  the  Hegelian  logic, 
322  ;  its  division,  323 

Logic,  Hegel's,  311,  322 

Logos,  history  and  use  of  the  word, 
57,  103,  104,  107,  108,  112,  312 

Lotze,  Rudolph  Hermann,  358  ; 
definition  of  philosophy,  358  ;  his 
metaphysic,  359 ;  ita  divisions, 
359;  his  method  borrowed  from 
Herbart,  360;  want  of  originality 
in  his  philosophy,  361 

Lucretius,  87 

Lykon,  46 

Maimon,  254,  258 

Mairaonides,  and  his  doctrines,  123 

Malebranche,  Nicholas,  155 ;  his 
main  problem,  156,  215 

Mauichfeanism,  102 

Mansel,  H.  L.,  377 

Marinos,  96 

Marx,  Karl,  341,  344 

Materialism,  influence  of,  on  con- 
duct, 212;  Lange's  history  of, 
d62 

Materialist  school,  French,  203 

Matter,  as  understood  by  Arist(jtle, 
68 

Maurice,  F.  D.,  history  of  philo- 
sophy, 13 

Mediaeval  philosophy,  111  ;  the 
earlier  schoolmen.  111  ;  the  Ara- 
bians and  Jews,  119;  the  later 
schoolmen,  124  ;  authorities,  130 

Megaric  school,  48 


414 


INDEX. 


Meletos,  46 

IMelissos,  work  of,  34 

Memory,  Leibnitz  on,  170 

Menander,  101 

Meno,  Plato's,  59 

Metaphysic,  Lotze's.  358,  359,  861 

Metaphysical  Foundations  of  Natu- 
ral Scimce,  Kant's,  225,  240 

Metaphj'sical  -  Physicists,  the  : 
Herakleitos,  36  ;  Empedoklts, 
38 ;  Anaxagoras,  39 ;  the  Atom- 
ists,  40 

Metaphysics,  Aristotle's,  67,  74 

Metempirics,  meaning  of  the  word, 
379 

Method,  the  Sokratic,  45 

Metrodoius,  82 

Michelet,  K.  L.,  edition  of  Hegel's 
lectures,  12 ;  his  summary  of  the 
Hegelian  system,  338,  344 

Mill,  James,  378 

Mill,  John  Stuart.  377 ;  his  work 
essentially  critical,  378  ;  its  value, 
378 

Mimansa,  the,  of  Jaimini,  18 

Minucius  Felix,  104 

Modern  philosophy,  transition  to, 
132 

Modem  philosophy  :  first  epoch, 
A.  The  Abstra'^-t-Dogmatic  Sys- 
tems, 144 ;  first  epocii,  b.  The 
Empirical-Sceptical  schools,  177; 
second  epoch,  Kant  and  the  Post- 
Kantians,  214 

Modes,  the,  of  Spinoza,  160 

Monadology,  Leibnitz's,  173 

Mysticism,  German,  of  the  four- 
teenth and  fifteenth  centuries, 
130 

Mythology  distinguished  from  philo- 
sophy, 2 

Nature,  philosophy  of,  Schelling's, 

284 ;  Hegel's,  327 
Neo-Hegelian     fcchool,     390  ;      its 

doctrines,  390 ;    its   importance, 

393 
Neo-Platonism,    89 ;     its    seat    in 

Alexandria,   89;   Philo,   89;  the 

characteiistic  of  the  school,  90; 


struggle  of,  with  Christianity,  9i 
Numenius  and  Ammonius  Sacca 
92  ;  Plotinus,  92  ;  the  Xe 
Platonic  trinity,  94 ;  Porphyr 
94 ;  Jamblichos,  94  ;  Hypati 
95 ;  Proklos,  95  ;  Marinots,  9i 
Isidore,  96  ;  Damascius,  96  ;  tl 
school  closed  by  Justinian,  91 
decline  of  classic  civiiisatio 
96 

Neo-Pythagorean  school,  88 

Nettesheim,  Cornelius  Agrippa,  vc  i 
138 

Nicolas  of  Chusa,  135,  139 

Nominalism  and  Kealism,  conti 
versy  between  115 

Nourrisson,  J.  F.,  history  of  phil 
sophy,  13 

Nuvalis,  286 

Novum  Organum,  Bacon's,  179 

Numenius,  92 

Nyaya,  the,  of  Gotama,  18 

Occam,  William  of,  128 ;  doctrin 
129;  else  of  scholasticism,  13 

Okeii,  287 

Ophites,  the,  102 

Organon,  Aristotle's,  75 

Orieutals,  qua^i-philosophy  of  tl 
15;  Egyptian,  15;  Semitic,  1 
Medo-Persian,  16;  Chinese,  1 
Indian,  17;  authorities,  20 

Oriuen,  105  ;  his  position  in  Chui 
history,  106 

Paracelsus,  139 ;  character  a 
travels,  139  ;  his  cosmologi' 
system,  140 
Paralogisms  of  the  pure  reason,  2 
Parmenides,  philosophy  of,  33,  4i 
Parmenides,  Plato's,  55,  57 
Party,  difterences  in  a,  not  a  sign 

its  decay,  337 
Paulicianism,  102 
Perception,     explanation     of, 
Empedokles,  3:*;  by  the  Atomis 
41 ;  difference  between  percepti 
and  feeling,  179  ;  mechanical  ( 
planation   of,   opposed  by  Le 
nitz,  169 


INDEX. 


415 


tripatetics,  orii^in  of  their  name; 
Gt) ;  their  work,  77 

essimism,  Schopenhauer  the 
founder  of  modern,  2:;i),  296 

Vi,r.<h,  Plato's,  50,  58 

li.^jdrus,  Plato's,  59 

\^h('nomenolo(jij  of  the  Mind,  Hegel's, 
:U  1,317,  318,319,821,  322 

'hilebos,  Plato's,  59,  62 

Miilippus,  77 

iiilo,  89 ;  his  doctrines,  90 ;  the 
characteristic  of  his  school,  90 

Philo  of  Larissa,  77 

liilosophie  Positive,  Comte's,  365, 
367,  369,  370,  372,  373 

'liilosophy,  the  problem  of,  1 ;  its 
scope,  2 ;  ancient  and  modern 
definitions  of  philosophy,  3,  358  ; 
modern  perversion  of  the  word, 
4 ;  ancient  division  into  logic, 
physic  and  ethic,  5;  modern 
division  into  theory  of  know- 
ledge, ontology  and  cosmology 
(including  psychology),  6 ;  philo- 
sophy become  a  profitable  pro- 
fession. So ;  state  of,  in  the  second 
half  of  the  eighteenth  century, 
217:  task  of,  258;  problem  of 
transcendental  philosophy,  280  ; 
Lotze's  definition  of,  358  ;  Lewes 
on  the  aim  of,  380 ;  unity  of,  39 1 ; 
rarity  of  true  philosophical  in- 
sight, 395;  explanation  of  the 
apparent  circularity  of  movement 
in,  396  ;  relations  between  science 
and  philosophy,  comprehensive- 
ness of  philosophy,  397  ;  the  end 
of  philosophy,  398;  the  purpose  of 
the  world,  400 ;  the  immediate 
pursuit  of  pleasui'e  not  the  end  of 
progress,  401 ;  the  dechne  of  the 
ethical  religions,  402 ;  humanity 
the  highest  actual  realisation  of 
the  world-principle,  404  ;  the 
future  of  philosopliy,  404 

Philosophy  of  the  Vncoiiscious,  Hart- 
raann's,  352,  357 
hysics,  Aristotle's,  72 
Ll^icus,  John,  133 

iato,  birth  and  youth,  54 ;  studies 


I  and  travels,  54 ;  school  in  Athens 
j      founded,  54  ;  death,  55 

Plato's  philosophy :  definition  of 
philosophy,  3 ;  his  doctrines  not 
derived  from  Sokrates,  21 ;  his 
school  complementnry,  not  op- 
posed, to  that  of  Aristotle,  51 ; 
his  philosophy  combining  the 
essence  of  all  pre-Sokratic  philo- 
sophies with  that  of  Sokrates,  53 ; 
exegesis,  55 ;  division  into  dia- 
lectics, physics,  and  ethics,  55 ; 
'  common  sense '  attacked,  55  ; 
dialectics  the  highest  stage  of 
philosophy,  56 ;  object  of  the 
dialectical  dialogues  of  Plato, 
57 ;  his  system  of  ideas,  58 ; 
the  •  highest  idea '  the  object  of 
dialectics,  59  ;  doctrine  of  remi- 
niscence, 59  ;  physical  specula- 
tions, 60 :  cosmical  theory,  61 ; 
definition  of  virtue,  62;  his 
ideal  commonwealth,  63;  Plato 
the  founder  of  the  '  theory  of 
knowledge,'  64 ;  nature  of  his 
philosophy,  64 ;  bibliography, 
76 ;  referred  to,  25,  66.  6S,  73,  91, 
103,  112,  117,  133,  161,  294,  313, 
346,  396 

Pleroma,  the,  101 

Plethon,  133 

Plotinus,  92  ;  his  doctrine,  93 ;  the 
Neo-Platonic  trinity,  94 

Poetics,  Aristotle's,  74 

Polemon,  73 

Politics,  Aristotle's,  73 

Politique  Positive,  Comte's,  366 

Polos,  43 

Polystratus,  82 

Porphyry,  94 

Port-Koy.il  Logic,  155 

Posidonius,  80 

Positivism,  founded  by  Comte, 
365  ;  its  principles,  367 

Pre-Sokratic  scliools  of  philosophy, 
23;  Ionian  schools,  23;  Italian 
school,  29;  Eleatic  school,  33; 
the  metaphysical  physicists,  36  ; 
transition  to  Sokrates,  42 

Princijples  of  Biology,  Spencer's,  388 


416 


INDEX. 


Principles  of  Human  Knowledge. 
Berkeley's,  189 

Problems  of  Life  and  Mind,  Lewes's. 
379 

Prodikos,  42,  44,  45 

Proklos  and  his  doctrine,  95 

Proleqomena  to  every  future  Meta- 
physic,  Kant's,  225,  230,  235,  239, 
246,  248 

Proslogium,  j^nselm's,  114 

Protagoras,  42 

PsycLology  to  be  considered  a 
department  of  philosophy,  6; 
Fichte's  opinion,  258 

Punishment,  purpose  of,  113 

Pyrrho,  77,  83 ;  his  doctrines,  83 

Pyrrhonistic  Hypotyposes,  the,  of 
Sextus  Empiricus,  86 

Pythagoras:  definition  of  philo- 
sophy, 3  ;  life,  29  ;  influence,  30 

Pythagorean  system,  30,  (5S  ;  funda- 
mental doctrine  of  number,  30  ; 
extension  of  theory,  31,  52  ;  cos- 
mology, 32  ;  variations  in,  from 
being  unwritten  by  its  founder, 
32 

Eeason,  superiority  of  the  practical 
over  the  pure,  249 

Keeent  and  current  philosophy,  \ 
352;  Hartmann,  352;  L  .fzH, 
358 ;  Diihring,  361 ;  Lange,  362 ; 
tendency  of  German  philosophers 
towards  historical  research,  364 ; 
Comte,  364;  J.  S.  Mill,  377; 
Bain,  378 ;  Lewes,  379  ;  Spencer, 
380 ;  the  Neo-Hegelian  school, 
390 

Reformation,  the  German,  134 

Eeid,  Thomas,  201 ;  axioms,  201 ; 
criticism  on  Hume,  2()2 

Eeinhold,  Ernst,  history  of  philo- 
sophy, 11 

Eeinhold,  K.  L.,  on  the  Kantian 
philosophy,  253,  258 

Eeligion,  Hegel's  philosophy  of,  334 

Eeminiscence,  Plato's  doctrine  of, 
59 

E' naissanoe,  philosophy  of  the, 
132;     Plethon,     133;     Ficinus, 


133;    Picus,   133;    the   Germat 
Eeformation,      134 ;       Giordanc 
Bruno,  134;  Campanella,  137 
Eepuhlic,  Plato's,  56,  62,  63 
l^euchlin,  Johannes,  137,  138 
Eichter,  Kant's  influence  on,  253 
Eitter,  history  of  philosophy,  11 
Eixner,  history  of  philosophy,  11 
Ei>man  and  Antiquarian  period  ol 
philosophy,  85  ;  characterised  bj 
exposition  of  older  doctrines,  85 
-^uesidemus,  86;  the  later  Seep' 
tics,  86 ;  the  Sextians,  87  ;  Cicero 
87 ;  Neo-Pythagoreans,  88 
Eoscelliuus,  115 
Kosenkranz,  312,  336,  33S,  344 
Eousseau,  206 
Euge,  Arnold,  343 

Sabelli^ns  the,  107 

St.  Auguatine  of  Hippo :  see  Augus- 
tine 

Sankhya,  the,  of  Kapila,  18 

Saturninus,  101 

Scepticism,  arguments  in  favoui 
of,  86 

Sceptics,  the,  83;  their  doctrines 
83  ;  not  original,  84  ;  authorities 
84 

Schelling,  Frederick  William  Jo' 
seph,  278 

Schelling's  philosophy :  definitior 
of  pldlosophy,  4 ;  the  '  systeu 
of  identity,'  278  ;  the  problem  o 
philosophy,  279 ;  nature-philo 
sophy,  279  ;  transceudenta 
philosophy,  280;  division  of  th< 
process  of  the  production  of  tht 
real  into  three  .>tage8,  281 
category  of  reciprocity,  281 
Schelling's  practical  philosophy 
282 ;  the  main  difference  betweer 
Schelling  and  Fichte,  283;  philo- 
sophy of  art,  283;  philosophy  oj 
nature,  284;  correspondence  oi 
Schelling  with  Fichte  and  Leib- 
nitz, 285;  Schelling's  later  ten- 
dency to  mysticism,  286 ;  his 
system  no  great  advance  on 
Fichte's,  286  ;  his  followers,  287 ; 


INDEX. 


417 


retrospect  and  criticism,  347; 
referred  to,  288,  300,  334,  3i7, 
353 

k'hiller,  Kant's  influence  on,  253 

>chlegel,  286 

Schmidt,  Dr. :  see  Stimer,  Max 

Schoolmen,  the  earlier,  111 ;  Eri- 
gena.  111;  Anselm,  114;  Abe- 
lard,  116 

choolmeu,  the  later,  124;  Al- 
bertus  Macrnus,  124;  Thomas 
Aquinas,  125  ;  Duns  Scotus,  127; 
William  of  Occam,  128 

Schopenhauer,  Arthur  :  life,  289  ; 
works,  289 

Schopenhauer's  philosophy :  defi- 
nition of  philosophy,  4 ;  position 
of  Schopenhauer's  philosophy, 
288  ;  the  four  forms  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  causality,  290;  separation 
of  the  will  from  the  intellect, 
291 ;  use  of  the  term  '  will,'  293 ; 
the  body  the  objectivation  of  the 
will,  294 ;  on  the  nature  of  will, 
295 ;  pessimism,  296 ;  place  of 
the  fine  arts  in  the  presentment 
of  the  will's  objectivation,  296 ; 
of  art,  297 ;  of  music,  298 ;  art 
a  quietude  of  the  will,  298 ;  the 
will-to-live,  299 ;  the  merit  of 
Schopenhauer's  work,  300;  his 
followers,  301 ;  retrospect  and 
criticism,  348 
chulze,  254,  258 

■>chwegler,  Albert,  history  of  philo- 
sophy, 12,  14 

"science  and  ])hilosophy,  relations 
between,  381,  397 

Science,  special,  distinguished  from 
philosophy,  2 

Segregation,  principle  of,  387 

Beneca,  87 

^ensationism  of  Condillac,  204 

5eth,  Andrew,  390 

Sextian  school,  87 

Sextius,  87 

5extus  Clodius,  88 

^extus  Empiricus,  86 

Shakespeare,  Bruno's  possible  in- 
fluence on,  135 


Simonians,  the,  100 

Social  Contract,  Kousseau's,  182, 
206 

Society,  Hobbes'  theory  of,  182 

Sociology  not  founded  by  Comte, 
373 

Sokrates :  birth,  44 ;  studies  and 
public  life,  44  ;  philosophy,  45  ; 
method,  45 ;  condemnation  and 
death,  46 ;  the  blame  of  his  ac- 
cusers exaggerated,  46 ;  the  revo- 
lution in  thought  due  to  him,  47 ; 
the  apostle  of  self-knowledge,  52 

Sokratic  Schools:  philosophv  of 
Sokrates,  45 ;  his  philosopliy  a 
method  rather  than  a  doctrine, 
47;  minor  Sol^ratic  scliools,  48; 
the  Megaric  school,  48 :  the 
Cyrenaic  school,  48 ;  the  Cynic 
school,  49 ;  referred  to,  57,  64,  91 

Sophistes,  Plato's,  57 

Sophists,  school  of  the,  42,  52  ;  its 
teachers,  42;  its  opposition  to 
earlier  philosophies,  43 ;  decline, 
43 

Sophroniskos,  44 

Space,  according  to  Aristotle,  71 

Spencer,  Herbert ;  definition  of 
philosophy,  4 ;  his  philosophy, 
380 ;  distinction  between  the 
absolute  and  the  relative,  380 ; 
ultimate  scientific  ideas,  381 ; 
relation  of  philosophy  to  science, 
381 ;  definition  of  reality,  382  : 
his  test  of  truth,  382  ;  principle* 
of  the  persistence  of  force  and  its 
consequences,  383;  definition  of 
evolution,  384;  principles  of 
evolution,  384  ;  change  from 
homogeneity  to  heterogeneity, 
386 ;  change  from  indefiniteness 
to  definiteiiess,  387  ;  tendency  of 
evolution  towards  equilibration, 
387 ;  tendency  after  equilibration 
to  dissolution,  388 ;  his  Principles 
of  Biology  and  later  works,  388 ; 
his  merits  and  defects,  389 

Speusippus,  77 

Spinoza,  Baruch  de,  157;  his  capa- 
city for  scientific  exposition,  166; 

2  E 


418 


INDEX. 


Spinoza's  philosophy,  158,  215 ;  his 
method,  158 ;  errors  of  abstraction 
and  imagination  distinguished, 
158 ;  starting-point  of  his  system, 
159  ;  account  of  his  system,  160 ; 
anthropology,  165  ;  ethics,  165 ; 
success  of  Spinozism,  167 ;  autho- 
rities, 167 :  his  system  contrasted 
with  that  of  Leibnitz,  174;  re- 
ferred to,  168,  214,  396 

Stanley,  Thomas,  history  of  phi- 
losophy, 10 

State,  function  of  the,  63,  200 

Stewart,  Dugald,  203 

Stilpo,  78 

Stirner,  Max,  340 ;  the  Individual 
and  his  Property,  342 

Stoics,  the,  their  definition  of  phi- 
losophy, 3 ;  their  doctrines,  78, 
80 ;  their  logic,  78 ;  physics, 
79 ;  ethics,  79 ;  Stoicism  pri- 
marily an  ethical  movement, 
80 

Strato.  78 

Strauss,  David  Friedrich,  338,  339, 
341  ;  his  Lehen  Jesu,  339  ; 
Chridian  Dogmatics  in  their 
Development,  &c.,  339 

Stromata,  the,  of  Clement  of  Alex- 
andria, 104 

Substance,  Descartes'  definition  of, 
150 

Syncretists,  work  of  the,  85,  87 

Synechology,  305 

Syrian  Gnostics,  100 ;  Menander, 
101 ;  Satuminus,  101 ;  Tatian, 
101 ;  Bardesanes,  101 ;  doctrines, 
101 

Systeme  de  la  Nature,  d'  Holbach's, 
210,  211,  213 

Tatian,  101 

Tauler,  Johannes,  131 

Teunemann,  history  of  philosophy, 
11,13 

Thales  :  life,  23 ;  knowledge,  23  ; 
his  claim  to  be  the  founder  of 
philosophy,  24  ;  his  central  doc- 
trine, 24 

Tlmtaitusy  Plato's,  55,  57,  62 


Theology  distinguished  from  phi 
losophy,  2 

Theology,  Kant's  criticism  of  ra^ 
tional,  247 

Theophilus,  104 

Theophrastus,  77 

Theory  of  Knowledge,  fundamental  . 
axioms  of  the,  258 

Therapeutse,  the,  90 

Thomasius,  Jacobus,  history  of 
philosophy,  10 

Thrasymachos,  43 

Tieck,  286 

Tiedemann,  history  of  philosophy,  11 

TimoRus,  Plato's,  60,  61,  62 

Time,  according  to  Aristotle,  71 

Tracy,  Testutt  de,  213 

Transcendental,  meaning  of  the 
word,  229 

Transitional  thought,  98  ;  the 
attitude  of  Christianity,  98  ;  the 
Gnostics,  100;  the  Christian 
Fathers,  103 

Treatise  of  Human  Nature^  Hume's, 
193,  196,  197,  199 

Trinity ;  the  Neo-Platonic,  dis- 
tinguished from  the  Christian, 
94 ;  the  doctrine  of  the,  the 
foundation  of  dogmatic  Christi- 
anity, 106 

Ueberweg,  history  of  philosophy, 

12,14 
Unknowable,  the,  383 
Upanischads,  the,  17 

Vaisehika,  the,  of  Kanada,  18 
Valentinus,  100 

Vedanta,  the,  of  Badarayana,  18 
Virtue,  Plato's  definition  of,   63; 

Epicurean  idea  of,  81 
Vischer,  338 

Vision,  Berkeley's  theory  of,  192 
Voltaire,  206 

Wagner,  J.  J.,  287 
Wallace,  Edwin,  390 
Wallace,  William,  390 
Weber,  Alfred,  history  of  philoso- 
phy, 13 


INDEX. 


419 


lii  Veifise,  criticism  of  the  Hegelian 
system,  338 

iVill :  Schopenhauer's  use  of  the 
word,  293 :  nature  of  the,  295 ; 
art  a  quietude  of  the,  298; 
Hartmanii  on  the  conjunction  of 
will  and  intelligence,  353 

Vill  in  Nature,  Schopenhauer's, 
289  292 

jVill-to-live,  the,  299 

Wissenscliaftslehre,     Ficht^'s,    257, 

!  261,  277 

jVolff,  Christian,  definition  of  phi- 
losophy, 3 ;    life,  175 ;    his  doc- 

I  trines,  175 

W'orld  as  Will  and  Presentation, 


Schopenhauer's,  289,   293,    290, 
298,  299,  300 

Xenocrates,  77 

Xenophanes ;    life,    33 ;    theistic 

tendency  of  writings,  33 
Xenophon,  44,  48 

Yoga,  the,  of  Patanjali,  18 

Zeller,  definition  of  philosophy,  4 
Zeno  of  Sidon,  82 
Zeno  the  Cyprist,  78 
Zeno    the    Eleatic,    philosophical 
work,  34 


CATALOGUE   OF 

BO  HNS    LIBRARIES. 


X.B.—It  is  requested  that  all  orders  be  accompanied  by 
paymefit.  Books  are  sent  carriage  free  on  the  receipt  of  the 
published  price  in  stamps  or  otherwise. 

The  Works  to  which  the  letters  '  N.  5.'  {denotijig  New 
Style)  are  appended  are  kept  in  neat  cloth  bindings  of  various 
colours,  as  well  as  in  the  7'egular  Library  style.  All  Orders 
are  executed  in  the  New  binding,  unless  the  contrary  is  ex- 
pressly stated. 

Complete  Sets  or  Separate  Volumes  can  be  had  at  short 
notice,  half-bound  in  calf  or  morocco. 


New   Volumes  of  Standard  Works  in  the  various  branches 

of  Literature  are  constantly  being  added  to  this  Series,  which 

is  already  unsurpassed  in   respect  to  the  number,  variety,  and 

cheapjiess  of  the  Works  contained  in  it.     The  Publishers  have 

to  anfiounce  the  following  Volumes  as  recently  issued  or  now 

in  preparation  : — 

Bos  well's  Life  of  Johnson.    New  Edition.    6  vols. 

[^Ready,  see  p.  i. 

Vasari's  Lives  of  tlie  Painters.     Additional  Notes  by 
J.  P.  Richter.  Ready,  see  p.  8. 

Koger  Ascham's  Scholemaster.    Edited  by  Prof.  Mayor. 

Grimm's  German  Tales.    2  vols.    With  the  Notes  of  the 
Original.  \_Rcady^  sec  p.  5. 

Coleridge's  Table-Talk,  &c.  IReady,  seep.  4. 

Coleridge's  Miscellaneous  "Works.  \_In  the  press. 

Manual  of  Philosophy.    By  E.  Belfort  Bax.    i  vol. 

Goldsmith's  Works.    Vols.  I.  and  II.  \_Ready,  seep.  5. 

Fairholt's  History  of  Costume.  \_In  the  press. 

Hoffmann's  Stories.     Translated  by  Major  Ewing. 

[//^  the  press. 


London  :  G.  BELL  &  SONS,  4  York  Street,  Covent  Garden. 


/tiiiuaiy,  18S5. 


BOHN'S    LIBRARIES. 


STANDARD    LIBRARY. 

294  fWo.  a/  Jx.  61/.  tach,  fxce/^iing  i/iosc  marked  otheriuise.  (51/.  10^-.  (yd.  per  set,) 


ADDISON'S  Works.  Notes  of  Bishop 
Hurd.  Short  Memoir,  Portrait,  and  8 
Plates  of  Medals.     6  vols.     .V.  .S". 

This   is    the   most  complete    edition   of 
Addison's  Works  issued. 

ALFIERI'S  Tragedies.  In  English 
Verse.  With  Notes,  Arguments,  and  In- 
troduction, by  E.  A.  Bowring,  C.B.  2  vols. 
N.S. 

AMERICAN  POETRY.  — .9.6  Fociry 
0/  A)Hcrica. 

ASCHAM'S  Scholemaster.  Edit,  by 
by  Prof.  J.  E.  B.  Mayor.        \_Iu  tJte press. 

BACON'S    Moral    and    Historical 

Works,  including  Essays,  Apophthegms, 
Wisdom  of  the  Ancients,  New  Atlantis, 
Henry  VII.,  Henry  VIII.,  Elizabeth, 
Henry'  Prince  of  Wales,  History  of  Great 
Britain,  Julius  Caesar,  and  Augustus  Caesar. 
With  Critical  and  Biographical  Introduc- 
tion and  Notes  by  J.  Devey,  M.A.  Por- 
trait.    N.  S. 

—  See  also  Philosophical  Library. 

BALLADS  AND  SONGS  of  the  Pea- 
santry of  England,  from  Oral  Recitation, 
private  MSS.,  Broadsides,  &c.  Edit,  by 
R.  Bell.    N.  S. 

BEAUMONT      AND       FLETCHER. 

Selections.  With  Notes  and  Introduction 
by  Leigh  Hunt. 

BECKMANN  (J.)  History  of  Inven- 
tions, Discoveries,  and  Origins.  With 
Portraits  of  Beckmann  and  James  Watt. 
2  vols.    N.S. 

BELL  (Robert).— .5"<7<r  Ballads,  CJiaucer, 
G  reef  I. 

BOSW^ELL'S  Life  of  Johnson,  with 
the  TOUR  in  the  HEBRIDES  and 
JOHNSONIANA.  New  Edition,  with 
Notes  and  Appendices,  by  the  Rev.  A. 
Napier,  M.A.,  Trinity  College,  Cam- 
bridge, Vicar  of  Holkham,  Editor  of  the 
Cambridge  Edition  of  the  '  Theological 
Works'of  Barrow.'  With  Frontispiece  to 
each  vol.     6  voh.    iV,.S\ 


BREMER'S       (Frederika)      W^orks. 

I        Trans,  by  M.  Howitt.  Portrait.  4  vols.  N.S. 

!    BRINK  (B.  T.)  Early  English  Litera- 

!         ture  (to  Wicllf).     By  Bernhard  Ten  Brink. 
I        Trans,  by  Prof.  H.  M.  Kennedy.     N.  S. 

I    BRITISH  POETS,  from  Milton  to  KIrke 
I        White.     Cabinet  Edition.     With  Frontis- 
piece.    4  vols.     N.  S. 

BROWNE'S   (Sir    Thomas)   Works. 

Edit,  by  S.  Wilkin,  with  Dr.  Johnson's 
Life  of  Browne.     Portrait.     3  vols. 

'    BURKE'S  Works.    6  vols.    .V.  .?. 

!    Speeches  on  the  Impeachment 

i        of  Warren  Hastings  ;  and  Letters.     2  vols. 
;  N.S. 

j    Life.     By  J.  Prior.     Portrait.     .V.  .9. 

BURNS  (Robert).    Life   of.    By  J.  G. 

j        Lockhart,    D.C.L.     A  new   and   enlarged 
I        edition.     With  Notes  and  Appendices  by 
W.  S.  Douglas.     Portrait.     ^V.  6\ 

BUTLERS  (Bp.)  Analogy  of  Reli- 
gion; Natural  and  Revealed,  to  the  Con- 

I  stitutlon  and  Course  of  Nature  ;  with  Two 
Dissertations  on  Identity  and  Virtue,  and 

I  Fifteen  Sermons.  With  Introductions, 
Notes,  and  Memoir.     Portrait.     *V.  .S". 

CAMOEN'S    Lusiad,   or   the   Discovery 
I        of  India.     An  Epic    Poem.     Trans,    from 
i        the    Portuguese,    with    Dissertation,    His- 
torical Sketch,  and  Life,  by  W.  J.  Mickle. 
j        5th  edition.     N.  S. 

CARAFAS     (The)      of     Maddaloni. 

Naples  under  Spanish  Dominion.  Trans, 
by  Alfred  de  Reumont.  Portrait  of  Mas- 
saniello. 

CARREL.    The  Counter-Revolution 

in  England  for  the  Re-establishment  of 
Popery  under  Charles  II.  and  James  II., 
by  Armand  Carrel  ;  with  Fox's  History  of 

'        James  II.  and  Lord  Lonsdale's  Memoir  of 

j        James  II.     Portrait  of  Carrel. 

I    C ARRUTHERS.  —  >y^<?   Pope,  in   IlluS' 

1        t rated  Library. 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


GARY'S  Dante.  The  Vision  of  Hell, 
Purgatory,  and  Paradise.  Trans,  by  Rev. 
H.  F.  Gary,  M.A.  With  Life,  Chronolo- 
gical View  of  his  A^e,  Notes,  and  Index 
of  Proper  Names.     Portrait.     N.  S. 

This  is  the  authentic  edition,  containi-ng 
Mr.  Cary's  last  corrections,  with  additional 
notes. 

CELLINI  (Benvenuto).  Memoirs  of, 
by  himself.  With  Notes  of  G.  P.  Carpam. 
Trans,  by  T.  Roscoe.     Portrait.     N.  S. 

CERVANTES'  Galatea.  A  Pastoral 
Romance.    Trass,  by  G.  W.  J.  Gyll.    N.  S. 

Exemplary   Novels.      Trans,    by 

W.  K.  Kelly.     JV.  S. 

Don    Quixote    de    la    Mancha. 

Motteux's  Translation  revised.  With  Lock- 
hart's  Life  and  Notes.     2  vols.     N.  S. 

CHAUCER'S  Poetical  Works.  With 
Poems  formerly  attributed  to  him.  With  a 
Memoir,  Introduction,  Notes,  and  a  Glos- 
sary', by  R.  Bell.  Improved  edition,  with 
Preliminary  Essay  by  Rev.  W.  W.  Skeat, 
M.A.     Portrait.     4  vols.     N.  S. 

CLASSIC  TALES,  containing  Rasselas, 
Vicar  of  Wakefield,  Gulliver's  Travels,  and 
The  Sentimental  Journey.     N.  S. 

COLERIDGE  S  (S.  T.)  Friend.  A  Series 
of  Essays  on  Morals,  Politics,  and  Reli- 
gion.    Portrait.     N.  S, 

Confessions    of    an    Inquiring 

Spirit ;  and  Essays  on  Faith  and  the  Com- 
mon Prayer-book.  New  Edition,  revised. 
N.S. 

Aids  to  Reflection.    N.S. 

Table-Talk   and   Omniana.     By 

T.  Ashe,  B.A.     N.S. 

Lectures    on    Shakspere     and 

other  Poets.  Edit,  by  T.  Ashe,  B.A.  A\S. 
Containing  the  lectures  taken  down  in 
i3ii-i2  by  J.  P.  Collier,  and  those  de- 
livered at  Bristol  in  1813. 

Biographia  Literaria;  or.  Bio- 
graphical Sketches  of  my  Literary  Life 
and  Opinions ;  with  Two  Lay  Sermons. 
N.S, 

COMMINES.— .S-^^  P/ti7i/>. 

CONDE'S  History  of  the  Dominion 

of  the  Arabs  in  Spain.  Trans,  by  Mrs. 
Foster.  Portrait  of  Abderahmen  ben 
Moavia.     3  vols. 

COWPER'SCompleteWorks,  Poems, 

Correspondence,  and  Translations.  Edit, 
with  Memoir  by  R.  Southey.  45  En- 
gravings. 8  vols. 
COXE'S  Memoirs  of  the  Duke  of 
Marlborough.  With  his  original  Corre- 
spondence, from  family  records  at  Blen- 
heim. Revised  edition.  Portraits.  3  vols. 
*^*  An  Atlas  of  the  plans  of  Marl- 
borough's campaigns,  4to.  10s.  6d. 


COXE'S  History  of  the  House  of  Aus- 
tria. From  the  Foundation  of  the  Monarchy 
by  Rhodolph  of  Hapsburgh  to  the  Death  of 
Leopold  II.,  1218-1792.  By  Archdn.  Coxe. 
With  Continuation  from  the  Accession  of 
Francis  I.  to  the  Revolution  of  1848. 
4  Portraits.     4  vols. 

CUNNINGHAM'S  Lives  of  the  most 

Eminent  British  Painters.  With  Notes 
and  16  fresh  Lives  by  Mrs.  Heaton.  3V01S. 
N.  S. 

DEFOE'S  Novels  and  Miscellaneous 

Works.  With  Prefaces  and  Notes,  in- 
ducing those  attributed  to  Sir  W.  Scott. 
Portrait.     7  vols.     N.  S. 

DE  LOLME'S  Constitution  of  Eng- 

land,  in  which  it  is  compared  both  with  the 
Republican  form  of  Government  and  the 
other  Monarchies  of  Europe.  Edit.,  with 
Life  and  Notes,  by  J.  Macgregor,  M.P. 

EMERSON'S  Works.  3  vols.  Most 
complete  edition  published.     N.  S. 

Vol.  I.— Essays,  Lectures,  and  Poems. 

Vol.  II. — English  Traits,  Nature,  and 
Conduct  of  Life. 

Vol.  III. — Society  and  Solitude — Letters 
and  Social  Aims — Miscellaneous  Papers 
(hitherto  uncollected) — ^May-Day,  S:c. 

FOSTER'S  (John)  Life  and  Corre- 
spondence. Edit,  by  J.  E.  Ryland.  Por- 
trait.    2  vols.     N.  S. 

Lectures  at  Broadmead  Chapel. 

Edit,  by  J.  E.  Ryland.     2  vols.     A''.  S. 

Critical    Essays  contributed  to 

the  '  Eclectic  Review.'  Edit,  by  J.  E. 
Ryland.     2  vols.     N.  S. 

Essays  :  On  Decision  of  Charac- 
ter ;  on  a  Man's  writing  Memoirs  of  Him- 
self; on  the  epithet  Romantic;  on  the 
aversion  of  Men  of  Taste  to  Evangelical 
Religion.     N.  S. 

Essays  on  the  Evils  of  Popular 

Ignorance,  and  a  Discourse  on  the  Propa- 
gation of  Christianity  in  India.     N.  S. 

Fosteriana  :  selected  from  periodical 

papers,  edit,  by  H.  G.  Bohn.     55,     N.  S. 

FOX  (Rt.  Hon.  C.  3.)— See  CarreL 

GIBBON'S  Decline  and  Fall  of  the 

Roman  Empire.  Complete  and  unabridged, 
with  variorum  Notes ;  including  those  of 
Guizot,  Wenck,  Niebuhr,  Hugo,  Neander, 
and  others.  7  vols.  2  Maps  and  Portrait. 
N.S. 

GOETHE'S  Works.  Trans,  into  English 
by  E.  A.  Bowring,  C.B.,  Anna  Swanwick, 
Sir  Walter  Scott,  &c.  &c.     12  vols.     N.  S. 

Vols.  I.  and  II.— Autobiography  and  An- 
nals.    Portrait. 

Vol.  III.— Faust.     Complete. 


STANDARD  LIBRARY. 


JOETHE'S  '^ox\iS.-Continued. 

Vol.  IV.— Novels  and  Tales  :  containing 
Elective  Aftlnities,  Sorrows  of  Werther, 
The  German  Emigrants,  The  Good  Wo- 
men, and  a  Nouvelette. 

Vol.  v.— Wilhelm  IMeister's  Apprentice- 
ship. 

Vol.  VI.— Conversations  v/ith  Eckerman 
anJ  Soret. 

Vol.  VII. — Poems  and  Ballads  in  the  ori- 
ginal Metres,  including  Hermann  and 
Dorothea. 

Vol.  VIII.— Gotz  von  Berlichingen,  Tor- 
quato  Tasso,  Egmont,  Iphigenia,  Clavigo, 
Wayward  Lover,  and  Fellow  Culprits. 

Vol.  IX. —  Wilhelm  Meister's  Travels. 
Complete  Edition. 

Vol.  X.  —  Tour  in  Italy.  Two  Parts. 
And  Second  Residence  in  Rome. 

Vol.  XI.— Miscellaneous  Travels,  Letters 
from  Switzerland,  Campaign  in  France, 
Siege  of  Mainz,  and  Rhine  Tour. 

Vol.  XII. — Early  and  Miscellaneous 
Letters,  including  Letters  to  his  Mother, 
with  Biography  and  Notes.  Edited  by 
Edw.  Bell,  M.A. 

! —  Correspondence  with   Schiller. 
2  vols. — Sec  Schiller. 

GOLDSMITH'S  W^orks.    5  vols.    K.S. 
Vol.  I.— Life, Vicar  of  Wakefield,  Essays, 
and  Letters. 
Vol.  II.— Poems,  Plays,  Bee,  Cock  Lane 

Ghost. 

[VoIs.'III.  and  IV.  in  the  f>ress. 

i^REENE,  MARLOW,  and  BEN 

JONSON  (Poems  of).     With  Notes  and 

Memoirs  by  R.  Bell.     N.  S. 
fREGORYS    (Dr.)    The   Evidences, 

Doctrines,  and  Duties  of  the  Christian  Re- 
ligion. 
rRIMM'S  Household  Tales.  With  the 

Original  Notes.     Trans,  by  Mrs.  A.  Hunt. 

Introduction  by  Andrew  Lang,  M.A.      2 

vols.     N.  S. 
rUIZOT'S  History  of  Representative 

Government  in  Europe.     Trans,  by  A.  R. 

Scoble. 
—  English  Revolution  of  1640.  From 

the  Accession  of  Charles  I.  to  his  Death. 

Trans,  by  W.  Hazlitt.     Portrait. 

—  History  of  Civilisation.    From  the 

Roman  Empire  to  the  French  Revolution. 

Trans,  by  W.  Hazlitt.     Portraits.     3  vols. 

lALLS   (Rev.  Robert)  Works  and 

Remains.      Memoir  by   Dr._  Gregorj'  and 
Essay  by  T.  Foster.     Portrait. 
lAWTHORNE'S  Tales.    3  vols.    A'.  S. 

Vol.  I. — Twice-told  Tales,  and  the  Show 
Image. 

Vol.  II.— Scarlet  Letter,  and  the  House 
with  Seven  Gables. 

Vol.  III. — Transformation,  and  Blithe- 
dale  Romance. 


HAZLITTS  (W.)  Works.   6  vols.  A'. 6-. 

Table-Talk. 

The  Literature   of  the  Age    of 

Elizabeth  and  Characters  of  Shakespeare '.-i 

Plays.     N.S. 
English  Poets  and  English  Comic 

Writers.     N.  S. 
HAZLITT'S  (W.)  'WOYliB.— Continued. 

The  Plain  Speaker.    Opinions  ob 

Books,  Men,  and  Things.     N.  S. 

Round     Table.       Conversations     of 

James  Northcote,  R.A.  ;  Characteristics. 
A'.  .S-. 

Sketches  and  Essays,  and  Winter- 
slow.    A'.  6-. 

HEINE'S  Poems.  Translated  in  the 
original  Metres,  with  Life  by  E.  A.  Bow- 
ring,  C.B.     5J.     A^  S. 

HUNGARY :  its  History  and  Revo- 
lution, with  Memoir  of  Koesuth.    Portrait. 

HUTCHINSON  (Colonel).  Memoirs 
of.  By  his  Widow,  with  her  Autobio- 
graphy, and  the  Siege  of  Lathom  House. 
Portrait.     N.  S. 

IRVING'S  (Washington)  Complete 
Works.     15  vols.     A^.  6'. 

Life  and  Letters.    By  his  Nephew, 

Pierre  E.  Irving.  With  Index  and  a 
Portrait.     2  vols.     A''.  S. 

JAMES'S  (G.  P.  R.)  Life  of  Richard 

Coeur  de  Lion.  Portraits  of  Richard  and 
Philip  Augustus.     2  vols. 

Louis  XIV.     Portraits.     2  vols. 

JAMESON    (Mrs.)      Shakespeare's 

Heroines.  Characteristics  of  Women.  By 
Mrs.  Jameson.     A^.  ^. 

JEAN  PAUL.— 6-^^  Richter. 

JONSON  (Ben).  Poems  ot.— See  Greene. 

JUNIUS 'S  Letters.  With  Woodfall's 
Notes.  An  Essay  on  the  Authorship.  Fac- 
similes of  Handwriting.     2  vols.     N.  S. 

LA  FONTAINE'S  Fables.  In  English 
Verse,  with  Essay  on  the  Fabulists.  By 
Elizur  Wright.     JV.S. 

LAMARTINE'S  The  Girondists,  or 
Personal  Memoirs  of  the  Patriots  of  the 
French  Revolution.  Trans,  by  H.  T. 
Ryde.  Portraits  of  Robespierre,  Madame 
Roland,  and  Charlotte  Corday.     3  vols. 

The    Restoration   of  Mpnarchy 

in    France  (a  Sequel   to  The   Girondists). 

5  Portraits.     4  vols. 

The  French  Revolution  of  18  i8. 

6  Portraits.        n 

LAMB'S  (Charles)  Elia  and  Eliana. 

Complete  Edition.     Portrait.     A".  S. 
Specimens  of  English  Dramatic 

Poets   of  the   time   of  Elizabeth.     Notes, 

with  the  Extracts  from  the  Garrick  Plays. 

N.S. 


BONN'S  LIBRARIES. 


LAPPENBERG'S  England  under  the 

Anglo-Saxon  Kings.  'J Vans,  by  B.Thorpe, 
F.S.A.     2  vols.     .V.  S. 

LANZI'S  History  of  Painting  in 
Italy,  from  the  Period  of  the  Revival  of 
the  Fine  Arts  to  the  End  of  the  i8th 
Century.  With  Memoir  of  the  Author, 
Portraits  of  Raffaelle,  Titian,  and  Cor- 
reggio,  after  the  Artists  themselves.  Trans, 
by  T.  Roscoe.     3  vols. 

LESSING'S  Dramatic  Works.  Com- 
plete. P>y  E.  Bell,  M.A.  With  Memoir 
by  H.  Zimmern.     Portrait.     2  \ols.    X.  S. 

• Laokoon,  Dramatic  Notes,  and 

Representation  of  Death  by  the  Ancients. 
Frontispiece.     X.  S. 

IiOCKE'S  Philosophical  Works,  con- 
taining  Human  Understanding,  \yith  Bishop 
of  Worcester,  Malebranche's  Opinions,  Na- 
tural Philosophy,  Reading  and  Study. 
With  Preliminary  Discourse,  Analysis,  and 
Notes,  by  J.  A.  St.  John.  Portrait.  2  vols. 
X.  S. 

Life  and  Letters,  with  Extracts  from 

his  Common-place  Books.     By  Lord  King. 

LOCKHART  (J.  G.)-S£e  Burns. 

LONSDALE  (Lord).— .S^t-c  Carrel. 

LUTHER'S  Table-Talk.  Trans,  by  W. 
Hazlitt.  With  Life  by  A.  Chalmers,  and 
Lither's  Catechism.  Portrait  after 
Cranach.     .V,  S. 

■ Autobiography.— .TtY  Mkhclct. 

MACHIAVELLI'S  History  of  Flo- 
rence, The  Prince,  Savonarola,  Historical 

Tracts,  and  Memoir.     Portrait.     -V,  6". 
TvIARLOWE.     Poems  of.— .9^^  Greene. 
MARTINEAU'S     (Harriet)    History 

of  England  (including  History  of  the  Peace) 

from  1800-1846.     5  vols.    X.S. 
T.I  EN  Z  EL'S   History   of  Germany, 

from  the  Earliest  Period  to  the  Crimean 

War.     3  Portraits.     3  vols. 
TI I C  H  E  L  E  T '  S    Autobiography    of 

Luther.      Trans,   by   W.    Hazlitt.      With 

Notes.     X.S. 
The  French   Revolution   to   the 

Flight  of  the  King  in  1791.     ..V.  S. 
MIGNET'S  The  French  Revolution, 

Irom  1789  to  1814.     Portrait  of  Napoleon. 

-V.  S. 
MILTON'S   Prose  Works.    With  Pre- 

face,  Preliminary   Remarks  by  J.   A.  St. 

John,  and  Index.     5  vols. 
MIT  FORD'S    (Miss)    Our   Village. 

Sketches  of  Rural  Character  and  Scenery. 

2  Engj-avings.     2  vols.     X.  S. 
MOLIERE'S    Dramatic    Works.     In 

Knglish  Prose,   by  C.  H.  Wall.     With  a 

Life  and  a  Portrait.     3  vols.     X.  S. 
'  It  is  not  too  much  to'a^y  that  we  have 

l-ere    probably  as  good  a    translation   of 

Molierc  as  can  be  given.' — Acade/uj. 


MONTESQUIEU'S    Spirit    of  Laws.. 

Revised  Edition,  with  D'Alemberi's  Analy-  ' 
sis,  Notes,  and  ^lemoir.     2  vols.     .V.  S 

NEANDER     Dr.  A.)    History  of  the 

Christian  Religion  and  Church.  Trans,  by 
J.  Torrey.     With  Short  Memoir.     10  vols. 

Life  of  Jesus  Christ,  in  its  His- 
torical Connexion  and  Development.   _\".  .V. 

The   Planting  and  Training  of 

the  Christian  Church  by  the  Aposiles. 
With  the  Antignosticus,  or  Spirit  of  Ter- 
tuUian.     Trans,  by  J.  E.  Ryland.     2  vols. 

Lectures     on     the    History    of 

Christian  Dogmas.  Trans,  by  J.  E.  Ry- 
land.    2  vols. 

• Memorials  of  Christian  Life  in; 

the  Earlv  and  Middle  Ages;  including 
Light  in'  Dark  Places.  Trans,  by  J.  E. 
Ryland.  j 

OCKLEY  (S.)    History  of  the  Sara- 

cens  and  their  Conquests  in  Syria,  Persia, 
and  Egypt,  Comprising  the  Lives  of 
Mohammed  and  his  Successors  to  the 
Death  of  Abdalmelik,  the  Eleventh  Caliph. 
By  Simon  Ockley,  B.D.,  Prof,  of  Arabic' 
in  Univ.  of  Cambridge.  Portrait  of  Mo-! 
hammed. 

PERCY'S  Reliques  of  Ancient  Eng- 
lish Poetry,  consisting  of  Ballads,  Songs, 
and  other  Pieces  of  our  earlier  Poets,  with 
some  few  of  later  date.  With  Essay  on 
Ancient  Minstrels,  and  Glossary'.  2  vols. 
X.S. 

PHILIP   DE  COMMINES.    Memoirs 

of.  Containing  the  Histories  of  Louis  XI. 
and  Charles  VI I L,  and  Charles  the  Bold, 
Duke  of  Burgundy.  With  the  History  of 
Louis  XL,  by  J.  de  Troyes.  With  a  Life 
and  N^otes  by  A.  R.  Scoble.  Portraits. 
2  vols. 

PLUTARCH'S  LIVES.  Newly  Trans- 
lated,  with  Notes  and  Life,  by  A. 
Stewart,  ALA.,  late  Fellow  of  Trinity 
College,  Cambridge,  and  G.  Long,  M.A. 
4  vols.     A^.  S. 

POETRY  OF  AMERICA.    Selections 

from  One  Hundred  Poets,  from  1776  to 
1876.  With  Introductory  Review,  and 
Specimens  of  Negro  Melodj-,  by  W.  J. 
Linton.     Portrait  of  W.  Whitman.     X.  S. 

RANKE  (L.)    History  of  the  Popes, 

their  Church  and  State,  and  their  Conflicts 
with  Protestantism  in  the  i6th  and  17th 
Centuries.  Trans,  by  E.  Foster.  Portraits 
of  Julius  II.  (after  Raphael),  Innocent  X. 
(after  ^'■elasquez),  and  Clement  VII.  (aftei 
Titian).     3  vols.     X.  S. 

History  of  Servia.    Trans,  by  Mrs. 

Kerr.  To  which  is  added,  The  Slave  Pro- 
vinces of  Turkey,  byCyprien  Robert.  ^V.  .S". 

REUMONT  (Alfred  de).— ^-^v:  Cara/^is. 


f  Law;, 


Tofth 


itsHii 


.ining 


itory 

.'■IS 

iLife 
ie  SaK 


entEii! 

Poeti, 

.  Essay  i 
7. 

Menoii 

s  the  Boil 
Histoiy 

\'6i]l 
Pm- 

jly  Te 
fe,  ly 
of  HM 

M,l 

lelectioi 

Jin  177* 
mew,  a 
bvW, 


;e  Pope! 


,  Porra    5 
VII.  (a:3 


■  Sliveft 


STANDARD  LIBRAR  \ 


lEYNOLDS'(Sir  J.)  Literary  "Works. 

With  Memoir  and  Reinaiks  by  H.  W. 
F.eechj-.     2  vols.     -\'.  6". 

LIGHTER  (Jean  Paul).  Levana,  a 
Treatise  on  Education  ;  together  with  the 
Autobiography,  and  a  short  Memoir.    N.S. 

—  Flower,  Fruit,  and  Thorn  Pieces, 

or  the  Wedded  Life,  Death,  and  Marriage 
of  Siebenkaes.  Translated  by  Alex.  Ewing. 

N.  S. 

Txt  only  complete  English  translation. 

XOSCOE'S  (W.)  Life  of  Leo  X.,  with 
Notes,  Historical  Documents,  and  Disser- 
tation  on   Lucretia    Borgia.     3   Portraits. 

c  \  ols. 

—  Lorenzo  de'  Medici,  called  '  The 
Magrnficent,'  with  Copyright  Notes, 
Poeius,  Letters,  &c.  With  Memoir  of 
Roscoe  and  Portrait  of  Lorenzo. 

I  US  SI  A,     History    of,    from    the 

earliest  Period  to  the  Crimean  War.  By 
V\'.  K.  Kelly.     3  Portraits.     2  vols. 

$OHILLER'S  Works.    6  vols.    A'.  .S. 

\'ol.  L — Thirty  Years'  War — Revolt  in 
the  Netherlands.  Rev.  A.  J.  W.  Morrison, 
M.A.     Portrait. 

Vol.  II. — Revolt  in  the  Netherlands, cw;/- 
//V/fi/— Wallenstein.  By  J.  Churchill  and 
S.  T.  Coleridge.— William  Tell.  Sir  Theo- 
dore rslartin.     Engraving  (after  Vandyck). 

Vol.  III.— Don  Carlos.  R.  D.  Boylan 
— Mary  .Stuart.  Mellish  —  Maid  of  Or- 
leans. Anna  Swanwick — Bride  of  Mes- 
sina. A.  Lodge,  M.A.  Together  with  the 
L'se  of  the  Chorus  in  Tragedy  (a  short 
Essay).     Engravings. 

These  Dramas  are  all  translated  in  metre. 

Vol.  IV. — Robbers — Fiesco — Love  and 
Intrigue — Demetrius — Ghost  Seer — Sport 
of  Divinity. 

The  Dramas  in  this  volume  are  in  prose. 

Vol.  v.— Poems.     E.  A,  Bowring,  C.B. 

Vol.  VI.— Essays,  iEsthetical  and  Philo- 
sophical, including  the  Dissertation  on  the 
Connexion  between  the  Animal  and  Spiri- 
tual in  Man. 


5CHILLER  and  GOETHE.  Corre- 
spondence between,  from  a.d.  1794-1805. 
V\'it'.i  Short  Notes  by  L.  Dora  Schmitz. 
2  vols.     N.  S. 


CHLEGEL'S   (F.)    Lectures   on  the 

Philosophy  of  Life  and  the  Philosophy  of 
Language.     By  A.  J.  W.  Morrison. 

—  The  History  of  Literature,  Ancient 

and  Modern. 

—  The  Philosophy  of  History.  With 
I^Ienioir  and  Portrait. 


SCHLEGEL'S  Works — Continued. 

Modern  History,  with  the  Lectures^ 

entitled  CH;sar  and  Alexander,  and  The 
Beginning  of  our  History.  By  L.  Puree!, 
and  R.  H.  Whitelock. 

.^Esthetic    and    Miscellaneous 

Works,  containing  Letters  on  Christiar> 
Art,  Essay  on  Gothic  Architecture,  Re- 
marks on  the  Romance  Poetry  of  the  Mid- 
dle Ages,  on  Shakspeare,  the  Limits  of  the 
Beautiful,  and  on  the  Language  and  Wis- 
dom of  the  Indians.     By  E.  J.  Millington. 

SCHLEGEL    (A.  W^.1    Dramatic  Art 

and  Literature.  By  J.  Black.  With  Me- 
moir by  A.  J.  W.  Morrison.     Portrait. 

SHAKESPEARE'S    Dramatic    Art. 

The  History  and  Character  of  .Shakspeare'.-- 
Plays.  By  Dr.  H.  Ulrici.  Trans,  by  L. 
Dora  Schmitz.     2  vols.     N.  S. 

SHERIDAN'S  Dramatic  Works.  Wit!^ 

Memoir.    Portrait  (after  Reynolds).    N.  S. 

SKEAT   :Rev.  W.  W.)-6\r  Chancer. 

SISMONDI'S  History  of  the  Litera- 
ture of  the  South  of  Europe.  With  Notes 
and  Memoir  by  T.  Roscoe.  Portraits  of 
Sismondi  and  Dante.     2  vols. 

The  specimens  of  early  Erench,  Italian, 
Spanish,  and  Portugese  Poetry,  In  English 
Verse,  by  Cary  and  others. 

SMITH'S  (Adam)  Theory  of  Moral 

Sentiments  ;  with  Essay  on  the  First  For- 
mation of  Languages,  and  Critical  Memoir 
byDugald  Stewart. 

SMYTH'S   (Professor)   Lectures    on 

Modern  History  ;  from  the  Irruption  of  the 
Northern  Nations  to  the  close  of  the  Ameri- 
can Re\"olution.     2  vols. 

Lectures  on  the  French  Revolu- 
tion.    With  Index.     2  vols. 

SOUTHEY.-.S-rr  Co-.vper,  Wesley,  and 
{liliistfated  Library)  Nelson. 

STURM'S    Morning    Communings 

with  God,  or  Devotional  Meditations  for 
Every  Day.  Trans,  by  W.  Johnstone,  M.A. 

SULLY.    Memoirs  of  the  Duke  of, 

Prime  Minister  to  Henrj-  the  Great.  With 
Notes  and  Historical  Introduction.  4  Por- 
traits.    4  vols. 

TAYLOR'S    (Bishop    Jeremy)    Holy 

Living  and  Dying,  with  Prayers,  contain- 
ing the  Whole  Duty  of  a  Christian  and  the 
parts  of  Devotion  fitted  to  all  Occasions. 
Portrait.     K.  S. 

THIERRY'S  Conquest  of  England  by 

the  Normans ;  its  Causes,  and  its  Conse- 
quences in  England  and  the  Continent. 
ByW.  Hazlltt.  With  short  Memoir.  2  Por- 
traits.    2  vols.     X,  S. 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


II 


TROYE'S  (Jean  A.e).—SeeP/ulipdeCom- 

})iines. 
ULRICI  '\Dx.')—See  Shakespeare. 
VASARI.  Lives  of  the  most  Eminent 

Painters,  Sculptors,  and  Architects.  By 
Mrs.  J.  Foster,  with  selected  Notes.  Por- 
trait. 6  vols.,  Vol.  VI.  being  an  additional 
Volume  of  Notes  by  J.  P.  Richter.    N.  S. 


I    "WESLEY,  the  Life  of,  and  the  Rise 

I        and  Progress   of  Methodism.     By  Robert 
Southey.     Portrait,     ^s.     N.  S. 

WHEATLEY.    A  Rational  niustra- 

tion  of  the  Book  of  Common  Prayer,  being 
the  Substance  of  everything  Liturgical  in 
all  former  Ritualist  Commentators  upon  the 
subject.     Frontispiece.     N.  S. 


HISTORICAL     LIBRARY. 

21  Volumes  at  ^s.  each.     (5/.  ^s.  per  set.) 


EVELYN'S  Diary  and  Correspond- 

dence,  with  the  Private  Correspondence  of 
Charles  I.  and  Sir  Edward  Nicholas,  and 
between  Sir  Edward  Hyde  (Earl  of  Claren- 
don) and  Sir  Richard  Browne.  Edited  from 
the  Original  MSS.  by  W.  Bray,  F.A.S. 
4  vols.  N.  S.  45  Engravings  (after  Van- 
dyke, Lely,  Kneiler,  and  Jamieson,  &c.). 

N.B. — This  edition  contains  130  letters 
from  Evelyn  and  his  wife,  contained  in  no 
other  edition. 


FEPYS'  Diary  and  Correspondence. 

With  Life  and  Notes,  by  Lord  Braybrooke. 
4  vols.  N.  S.  With  Appendix  containing 
additional  Letters,  an  Index,  and  31  En- 
gravings (after  Vandj'ke,  Sir  P.  Lely, 
Holbein,  Kneiler,  &c.). 


JESSE'S   Memoirs   of  the  Court  of 

England  under  the  Stuarts,  including  the 
Protectorate.  3  vols.  With  Index  and  42 
Portraits  (after  Vandyke,  Lely,  &c.). 

Memoirs  of  the  Pretenders  and 

their  Adherents.    7  Portraits. 

NU GENT'S    (Lord)    Memorials    of 

Hampden,  his  Party  and  Times.  With 
Memoir.  12  Portraits  (after  Vandyke 
and  others).     .V.  6". 

STRICKLAND'S  (Agnes)  Lives  of  the 

Queens  of  England  from  the  Norman 
Conquest.  From  authentic  Documents, 
public  and  private.  6  Portraits.  6  vols. 
N.S. 

Life  of  Mary  Queen   of  Scots. 

2  Portraits.     2  vols.     N.  S. 


I 


PHILOSOPHICAL    LIBRARY. 

15  Vols,  at  ^s.  each,  excepting  those  marked  othencise.     (3/.  95-.  ol.  per  sci^ 


BACON'S  Novum  Organum  and  Ad- 
vancement of  Learning.  With  Notes  by 
J.  Devey,  M.A. 

COMTE'S  Philosophy  of  the  Sciences. 

An  Exposition  of  the  Principles  of  the 
Cours  de  Philosophie  Positive.  By  G.  H. 
Lewes,  Author  of  '  The  Life  of  Goethe.' 

DRAPER  (Dr.  J.  W.)    A  History  of 

the  Intellectual  Development  of  Europe. 
2  vols.     N.  S. 

HEGEL'S  Philosophy  of  History.    By 

J.  Sibree,  M.A. 

KANT'S    Critique    of  Pure  Reason. 

By  J.  M.  D.  IMeiklejohn.     N.  S. 
Prolegomena  and  Metaphysical 

Foundations  of  Natural  Science,  with  Bio- 
graphy and  Memoir  by  E.  Belfort  Bax. 
Portrait.     N.  S. 


LOGIC,  or  the  Science  of  Inference. 

A  Popular  Manual.     By  J.  Devey. 

MILLER  (Professor).    History  Philo. 

sophically  Illustrated,  from  the  Fall  of  the 
Roman  Empire  to  the  French  Revolution. 
With  Memoir.     4  vols.     y.  6d.  each. 

SPINOZA'S  Chief  Works.  Trans,  with 
Introduction  by  R.  H.  M.  Elwes.  2  vols. 
N.S. 

Vol.   I. — Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus 
— Political  Treatise. 

Vol.    II. —  Improvement   of  the   Under- 
standing— Ethics— Letters. 

TENNEMANN'S  Manual  of  the  His- 
tory of  Philosophy.  Trans,  by  Rev.  A. 
Johnson,  M.A. 


ij 


THEOLOGICAL  AND  ANTIQUAIUAN  LIBRARIES. 


THEOLOGICAL    LIBRARY. 

IS  Vols,  at  5j.  each^  excepting  those  marked  othcmnse.     (3/.  13^.  6d.  per  set.) 


3LEEK.     Introduction  to    the   Old 

Testament.  By  Friedrich  Bleek.  Trans, 
under  the  supervision  of  Rev.  E.  Venables, 
Residentiary  Canon  of  Lincoln.  2  vols. 
N.S. 


Religion   of 


'Ourt 

liig  tin 


:  H I LLI N  GWORTH'S 

Protestants.     35-.  6d. 


3USEBIUS.     Ecclesiastical   History 

of  Eusebius  Pamphilius,  Bishop  of  Ca^sarea. 
Trans,  by  Rev.  C.  F.  Cruse,  IM.A.  With 
Notes,  Life,  and  Chronological  Tables. 


IVAGRIUS.    History.of  the  Church. 

— See  Thcodorct. 


"5  anf  SARD  WICK.  History  of  the  Articles 

of  Religion  ;  to  which  is  added  a  Series  of 
Documents  from  a.d.  1536  to  a.d.  1615, 
Ed.  by  Rev.  F.  Proctor.     N.  S. 


rials 


'::iyl 


HENRY'S  (Matthew)  Exposition  of 

the  Baok  of  Psalms.    Numerous  Woodcuts. 
esoftbi 
Norm    PEARSON  (John,  D.D.)    Exposition 

i      of  the  Creed.     Edit,  by  E.  Walford,  M.A. 
^[i      With  Notes,  Analysis,  and  Indexes.     N.S. 

f  Scots  . 


PHILO-JUD^US,    Works    of.      The 

Contemporary  of  Josephus.  Trans,  by 
C.  D.  Yonge.     4  vols. 

PHILOSTORGIUS.    Ecclesiastical 

History  of. — See  Sozoiiien. 

SOCRATES'   Ecclesiastical  History, 

Comprising  a  History  of  the  Church  from 
Constantine,  a.d.  305;  to  the  38th  year  of 
Theodosius  IL  With  Short  Account  of 
the  Author,  and  selected  Notes. 

SOZOMEN'S  Ecclesiastical  History. 

A.D.  324-440.  With  Notes,  Prefatory  Re- 
marks by  Valesius,  and  Short  Memoir. 
Together  with  the  Ecclesiastical  His- 
tory OF  Philostorgius,  as  epitomised  by 
Photius.  Trans,  by  Rev.  E.  Walford,  IvLA. 
With  Notes  and  brief  Life. 

THEODORET  and  EVAGRIUS.  His- 
tories of  the  Church  from  a.d.  332  to  the 
Death  of  Theodore  of  Mopsuestia,  a.d. 
427  ;  and  from  a.d.  431  to  a.d.  544.  With 
Memoirs. 

W^IESELER'S   (Karl)    Chronological 

Synopsis  of  the  Four  Gospels.  Trans,  by 
Rev.  Canon  Venables.     N.  S. 


ANTIQUARIAN    LIBRARY. 

35  V^ols.  at  5^-.  each.     {81.  i$s.  per  set.) 


ference. 


ryPhilo 
Falloftfe 


BINGLO-SAXON   CHRONICLE.  —  See 

Bede. 
asSER'S  Life  of  Alfred.— ^"^^  Six  O.  E. 

Chronicles. 
BEDE'S    (Venerable)    Ecclesiastical 

History  of  England.  Together  with  the 
Anglo-Saxon  Chronicle.  With  Notes, 
Short  Life,  Analysis,  and  Map.  Edit,  by 
J.  A,  Giles,  D.C.L. 

'*«1bOETHIUS'S  Consolation  of  Philo- 
sophy. King  Alfred's  Anglo-Saxon  Ver- 
sion of.  With  an  English  Translation  on 
opposite  pages.  Notes,  Introduction,  and 
Glossary,  by  Rev,  S.  Fox,  M.A.  To 
which  is  added  the  Anglo-Saxon  Version  of 
the  Metres  of  Boethius,  with  a  free 
Translation  by  Martin  F.  Tupper,  D.C.L. 

BRAND'S     Popular    Antiquities    of 

England,  Scotland,  and  Ireland.  Illus- 
trating the  Origin  of  our  Vulgar  and  Pro- 
vincial Customs,  Ceremonies,  and  Super- 
stitions. By  Sir  Henry  Ellis,  K.H.,  F.R.S. 
frontispiece.    3  vols. 


'Br.5.\»' 


:Uni 


CHRONICLES    of  the    CRUSADES. 

Contemporary  Narratives  of  Richard  Coeur 
de  Lion,  by  Richard  of  Devizes  and  Geof- 
frey de  Vinsauf ;  and  of  the  Crusade  at 
Saint  Louis,  by  Lord  John  de  Joinville. 
With  Short  Notes.  Illuminated  Frontis- 
piece from  an  old  MS. 

DYER'S  (T.  F.  T.)    British  Popular 

Customs,  Present  and  Past.  An  Account 
of  the  various  Games  and  Customs  asso- 
ciated with  different  Days  of  the  Year  in 
the  British  Isles,  arranged  according  to  the 
Calendar.  By  the  Rev.  T.  F.  Thiselton 
Dyer,  M.A. 

EARLY  TRAVELS  IN  PALESTINE. 

Comprising  the  Narratives  of  Arculf, 
Willibald,  Bernard,  Sajwulf,  Sigurd,  Ben- 
jamin of  Tudela,  Sir  John  Maundeville, 
De  la  Brocquiere,  and  Maundrell  ;  all  un- 
abridged. With  Introduction  and  Note? 
by  Thomas  Wright.     Map  of  Jerusalem. 


BONN'S  LIBRARIES. 


ELLIS  (G.)  Specimens  of  Early  En- 
glish INIetrical  Romances,  relatine:  to 
Arthur,  Merlin,  Guy  of  Warwick,  Richard 
Coeur  de  Lion,  Charlemagne,  Roland,  S:c. 
S:c.  With  Historical  Introduction  by  J.  O. 
Halliwell,  F.R.S.  Illuminated  Frontis- 
piece from  an  old  ]MS. 

ETHELWERD.      Chronicle    of.  — Sec 

Six  O.  E.  Chronicles. 

FLORENCE     OF    W^ORCESTER'S 

Chronicle,  with  the  Two  Continuations  : 
comprising  Annals  of  English  History 
from  the  Departure  of  the  Romans  to  the 
Reign  of  Edward  I.  Trans.,  with  Notes, 
1)y  Thomas  Forester,  M.A. 

GESTA  ROMANORUM,  or  Enter- 
taining Moral  Stories  invented  by  the 
Monks.  Trans,  with  Notes  by  the  Rev. 
Charles  Swan.     Edit,  by  W.  Hooper,  M.A. 

GIRALDUS  CAMBRENSIS'  Histori- 
cal Works.  Containing  lopography  of 
Ireland,  and  Histoiy  of  the  Conquest  of 
Ireland,  by  Th.  Forester,  MA.  Itinerary 
through  AVales,  and  Description  of  Wales, 
by  Sir  R.  Colt  Hoare. 

GEOFFREY     OF    MONMOUTH. 

Clironicle  of. — Sec  Six  O.  E.  Chronicles. 

GILD  AS.     Chronicle  of.— Sec  Six  O.  E. 

Chronicles. 

HENRY    OF    HUNTINGDON'S    His 

tory  of  the  English,  from  the  Roman  In- 
vasion to  the  Accession  of  Henry  II.  ; 
with  the  Acts  of  King  Stephen,  and  the 
Letter  to  Walter.  By  T.  P'orester,  M.A. 
Frontispiece  from  au  old  MS. 

INGULPH'S  Chronicles  of  the  Abhey 

of  Croyland,  with  the  Contintation  by 
Peter  of  P.lois  and  others.  Trans,  with 
Notes  by  H.  T.  Riley,  13.A. 

KEIGHTLEY'S  (Thomas)  Fairy  My- 
thology, illustrative  of  the  Romance  and 
Superstition  of  Various  Countries.  Frontis- 
piece by  Cruikshank.     N.  S. 

LEPSIUS'S    Letters   from    Egypt, 

Ethiopia,  and  the  Peninsula  of  Sinai ;  to 
which  are  added.  Extracts  from  his 
Chronolog>'  of  the  Egj-ptians,  with  refer- 
ence to  the  Exodus  of  the  Israelites.  By 
L.  and  J.  B.  Horner.  Maps  and  Coloured 
\'iew  of  Mount  Barkal. 

MALLET'S  Northern  Antiquities,  or 

an  Historical  Account  of  the  Manners, 
Customs,  Religions,  and  Literature  of  the 
Ancient  Scandinavians.  I'rans.  by  Bishop 
Percy.  With  Translation  of  the  Pkosk 
Edu.\,  and  Notes  by  J.  A.  Blackwell. 
Also  an  Abstract  of  the  '  Eyrbyggi.-i  Saga  ' 
by  Sir  Walter  Scott.  With  Glossary 
and  Coloured  Frontispiece. 


MARCO  POLO'S  Travels ;  with  Notes^ 
and    Introduction.      Edit,   by  T.   Wright. 

MATTHEW  PARIS'S  English  His- 
tory, from  1235  to  1273.  By  Rev.  J.  A. 
Giles,  I). CL.  With  P'rontispiece.  3  vols. — 
Sec  also  Kp£^er  0/  Jl'c/ulczrr. 

MATTHEW    OF    W^ESTMINSTER'S 

Flowers  of  History-,  especially  such  as  re- 
late to  the  affairs  of  Britain,  from  the  be- 
ginning of  the  World  to  A.D.  1307.  By 
C.  D.  Yonge.     2  vols. 

NENNIUS.      Chronicle   ot.—  Scj   Six 

O.  E.  Chronicles. 

ORDERICUS  VITALIS'  Ecclesiastical 

History  of  England  and  Normandy.  With 
Notes,  Introduction  of  Guizot,  and  the 
Critical  Notice  of  M._  Delille,  by  T. 
Forester,  M.A.  To  which  is  added  the 
Chronicle  of  St.  Evroult.  With  Gene- 
ral and  Chronological  Indexes.     4  vols. 

PAULI'S  (Dr.  R.)  Life  of  Alfred  the 

Great.  To  which  is  appsnded  Alfred's 
An-gi.o-Saxox  Version  of  Orosils.  With 
iiteral  Translation  interpaged,  Note-,  and 
an  Anglo-Saxon  Grammar  and  Glossary,, 
by  B.  Thorpe,  Esq.     Fro.-.tispiece. 

RICHARD    OF    CIRENCESTER. 

Chronicle  of. — Sec  Six  O.  E.  CJironiclcs. 

ROGER  DE  HOVEDEN'S  Annals  of 

English  History,  comprising  the  History 
of  England  and  of  other  Countries  of  Eu- 
rope from  A.D.  732  to  A.D.  1201.  With 
Notes  by  H.  T.  Riley,  B.A.     2  vols. 

ROGER  OF  W^ENDOVER'S  Flowers 

of  History,  comprising  the  History  or 
England  from  the  Descent  of  the  Saxons  to 
A.D.  1235,  formerly  ascribed  to  Matthew 
Pai-is.  With  Notes  and  Index  by  J.  A. 
Giles,  D.C.L.     2  vols. 

SEX  OLD  ENGLISH  CHRONICLES  : 

viz.,  Asser"s  Life  of  Alfred  and  the  Chroni- 
cles of  Ethelwerd,  Gildas,  Nennius,  Geof- 
frey of  Monmouth,  and  Richard  of  Ciren- 
cester. ?".dit.,  with  Notes,  by  J.  A.  Giles, 
D.C.L.     Portrait  of  Alfred. 

WILLIAM     OF     MALMESBURYS 

Chronicle  of  the  Kings  of  England,  from 
the  Earliest  Period  to  King  Stephen.  By 
Rev.  J.  Sharpe.  With  Notes  by  J.  A. 
Giles,  D.C.L.     Frontispiece. 

YULE-TIDE  STORIES.  A  Collection 
of  Scandina\ian  and  North-German  Popu- 
lar Tales  and  Traditions,  from  the  Swedish, 
Danish,  and  German.    Edit,  by  B.  Thorpe. 


giiihaii 


« lit  be. 


/ZZ  USTRA  TED  LIBRA  R  \ '. 


II 


''•'•J. A,   85  Vols,  at  5J-.  ^ar//,  excepting tho. 

"  ivols,-J 

LLEN'S  (Joseph,  R.N.)  Battles  of 
the  British  Navj-.  Revised  edition,  with 
Indexes  of  Names  and  Events,  and  57  Por- 
traits and  Plans.     2  vols. 

UNDERSEN'S   Danish   Fairy  Tales. 

By  Caroline  Peachey.  With  Short  Life 
and  120  Wood  Engravings. 

-J  i  &§.RIOSTO'S     Orlando     Furioso. 

English  Verse  by  W.  S.  Rose.  With  Notes 
and  Short  Memoir.     Portrait  after  Titian, 

'Miasticali  ^"d  24  Steel  Engravings.     2  vols. 

^^'f  ^ECHSTEIN'S  Cage   and   Chamber 

:,  ,.'?  Birds:  their  Natural  History,  Habits,  &c. 
'n  j  ''i  Together  with  Sweet's  Bkitish  War- 
SnJ  '^^■^'^^-  ^2  Plates  and  W^oodcuts.  N.  S. 
4 vol),  I or  with  the  Plates  Coloured,  75.  6d. 


ILLUSTRATED    LIBRARY. 

marked  othe}-7uise.     (23/.  2s.  6d.  per  set. ) 


JONOMI'S  Nineveh  and  its  Palaces. 

The  Discoveries  of  Botta  and  Layard 
applied  to  the  Elucidation  of  Holy  Writ, 
7  Plates  and  294  Woodcuts.     .V.  S. 


Ifred  the 

Will 

!iG!osar)^UTLER'S    Hudibras 
Notes   and   Biography 
Illustrations. 


ESTER 


Innals  oi 


^ATTERMOLE'S  Evenings  at  Had- 

don  Hall.  Romantic  Tales  pf  the  Olden 
Times.  With  24  Steel  Engravings  after 
Cattermole. 


Maiikf. 
kl.A, 


«CLES; 

-.eCkoni- 
;!D!,  Geof' 
ofCireH' 
,A.Gile: 


with    Variorum 
Portrait   and   28 


fEnJCHENA,  Pictorial,  Descriptive,  and 

Historical,  with  some  account  of  Ava  and 
the  Burmese,  Siam,  and  Anam.  Map,  and 
nearly  100  Illustrations. 

.^"^JCRAIK'S  (G.  L.)  Pursuit   of  Know- 

iM  "1  ledge  under  Difficulties.  Illustrated  by- 
Anecdotes  and  Memoirs.  Numerous  Wood- 
cut Portraits.    N.  S. 


■CRUIKSHANK'S  Three  Courses  and 

a  Dessert ;  comprising  three  Sets  of  Tales, 
West  Country,  Irish,  and  Legal ;  and  a 
Melange.  With  50  Illustrations  by  Cruik- 
shank.     A'.  S. 


ollectioJ 


— -  Punch  and  Judy.  The  Dialogue  of 
the  Puppet  Show  ;  an  Account  of  its  Origin, 
&c.  24  Illustrations  by  Cruikshank.   A'.  ^. 

—  With  Coloured  Plates.     7^-.  6d. 

DANTE,  in  English  Verse,  by  I.  C.  Wright, 
M.A.  _  With  Introduction  and  Memoir. 
Portrait  and  34  Steel  Engravings  after 
Flaxman.     A\  6". 


DIDRON'S  Christian   Iconography; 

a  History  of  Christian  Art  in  the  Middle 
Ages.  Trans,  by  E.  J,  Millington.  150 
Outline  Engravings. 


DYER  (Dr.  T.  H.)   Pompeii :  its  Build- 

ings  and  Antiquities.  An  Account  of  the 
City,  with  full  Description  of  the  Remain^ 
and  Recent  Excavations,  and  an  Itinerarj- 
for  Visitors.  By  T.  H.  Dyer,  LL.D. 
Nearly  300  Wood  Engravings,  Map,  and 
Plan.     -rs.Cd.    A\S. 

Rome :    History    of   the    City,   with 

Introduction  on  recent  E.xcavatioas.  8 
Engravings,  Frontispiece,  and  2  Maps. 

GIL    6LAS.     The    Adventures    of. 

From  the  French  of  Lesage  by  Smollett. 
24  Engravings  after  Smirke,  and  10  Etch- 
ings by  Cruikshank.     612  pages.     6^. 

GRIMM'S  Gammer  Grethel;  or,  Ger- 

man  Fairy  Tales  and  Popular  Stories, 
containing  42  Fairy  Tales.  By  Edgar 
Taylor.  Numerous  Woodcuts  after  Cruik- 
shank and  Ludwig  Grimm.     3J.  6d. 

HOLBEIN'S    Dance    of   Death   and 

Bible  Cuts.  Upwards  of  150  Subjects,  en 
graved  in  facsimile,  with  Introduction  and 
Descriptions  by  the  late  Francis  Douce 
and  Dr.  Dibdin.     js.  (xi. 

HOWITT'S  (Mary)  Pictorial  Calen- 
dar of  the  Seasons  ;  embodying  Aikin's 
Calendar  of  Nature.  Upwards  of  100 
Woodcuts. 

INDIA,  Pictorial,  Descriptive,   and 

Historical,  from  the  Earliest  Times.  100 
Engravings  on  Wood  and  Map. 

JESSE'S  Anecdotes  of  Dogs.  With 
40  Woodcuts  after  Harvej",  Bewick,  and 
others,     N.  S. 

With  34  additional   Steel    Engravings 

after  Cooper,  Landseer,  &c.   7^.  td.   N.  S. 

KING'S  (C.  W.)    Natural  History  of 

Gems    or    Decorative    Stones.       lUiastra- 
tions.     6s. 
Natural    History    of    Precious 

Stones  and  Metals.     Illustrations,     ts. 

Handbook   of  Engraved  G«ms. 

Numerous  Illustrations,     ts. 

KITTO'S  Scripture  Lands.  Described 
in  a  series  of  Historical,  Geographical,  and 
Topographical  Sketches.     42  Maps. 

With  the  Maps  coloured,  -js.  6d. 

KRUMMACHER'S  Parables.  40  lllus- 
trations. 

LINDSAY'S  (Lord)  Letters  on  Egypt, 

Edom,  and  the  Holy  Land.  36  Wood 
Engravings  and  2  Maps. 


12 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


LODGE'S     Portraits    of   Illustrious 

Personages  of  Great  Britain,  -vvith  Bio- 
graphical and  Historical  l^Iemoirs.  240 
Portraits  engraved  on  Stepl,  with  the 
respective  Biographies  unabridged.  Com- 
plete in  8  vols. 

LONGFELLOW'S    Poetical    Works, 

including  his  Translations  and  Notes.  24 
full-page  Woodcuts  by  Birket  Foster  and 
others,  and  a  Portrait.     N.  S. 

Without  the  Illustrations,  35.6^.   N.S. 

-  Prose  Works.  With  16  full-page 
Woodcuts  by  Birket  Foster  and  others. 

LOUDON'S  (Mrs.)  Entertaining  Na- 
turalist. Popular  Descriptions,  Tales,  and 
Anecdotes,  of  more  than  500  Animals. 
Numerous  Woodcuts.    N.  S. 

MARRY AT'S  (Capt.,  R.N.)  Master- 
man  Ready  ;  or,  the  Wreck  of  the  Pa<:ijic. 
(Written  for  Young  People.)  With  93 
Woodcuts.     3^.  dd.    N.  S. 

Mission;    or,  Scenes  in  Africa. 

(Written  for  Young  People.)  Illustrated 
by  Gilbert  and  Dalziel.     y.  6d.     N.  S. 

Pirate  and  Three  Cutters.  (Writ- 
ten for  Young  People.)  With  a  Memoir. 
8  Steel  Engravings  after  Clarkson  Stan- 
field,  R.A.     35.  6d.     N.  S. 

Privateersman.    Adventures  by  Sea 

and  Land  One  Hundred  Years  Ago. 
(Written  for  Young  People.)  8  Steel  En- 
gravings.    35.  6d.     N.  S. 

Settlers  in  Canada.    (Written  for 

Young  People.)  10  Engravings  by  Gilbert 
and  Dalziel.     3J.  6d.    N.  S. 

Poor     Jack.      (Written    for    Young 

People.)  With  16  Illustrations  after  Clark- 
son  Stanfield,  R.A.     3^.  6d.     N'.  S. 

MAXWELL'S  Victories  of  Welling- 
ton and  the  British  Armies.  Frontispiece 
and  4  Portraits. 

MICHAEL  ANGELO  and  RAPHAEL, 

Their  Lives  and  Works.  By  Duppa  and 
Quatremere  de  Quincy.  Portraits  and 
Engravings,  including  the  Last  Judgment, 
and  Cartoons.     N.  S. 

MILLER'S  History  of  the  Anglo- 
Saxons,  from  the  Earliest  Period  to  the 
Norman  Conquest.  Portrait  of  Alfred,  I\Iap 
of  Saxon  Britain,  and  12  Steel  Engravings. 

MILTON'S  Poetical  Works,  with  a 
Memoir  and  Notes  by  J.  Montgomerj^,  an 
Index  to  Paradise  Lost,  Todd's  Verbal 
Index  to  all  the  Poems,  and  Notes.  120 
Wood  Engravings.     2  vols.     N.  S. 

MUDIE'S  History  of  British  Birds. 

Revised  by  W.  C.  L.  Martin.  52  Figures  of 
Birds  and  7  Plates  of  Eggs.     2  vols.     N.S. 

With  the  Plates  coloured,  "js.  6d.  per  vol. 


NAVAL    and   MILITARY    HEROES; 

of  Great  Britain  ;  a  Record  of  British ! 
Valour  on  every  Day  in  the  year,  from  j 
William  the  Conqueror  to  the  Battle  of! 
Inkermann.  By  Major  Johns,  R.M.,  and 
Lieut.  P.  H.  Nicolas,  R.M.  Indexes.  24 
Portraits  after  Holbein,  Reynolds,  &c.   6^-. 

NICOLINI'S  History  of  the  Jesuits : 

their  Origin,  Progress,  Doctrines,  and  De- 
signs.    8  Portraits. 

PETRARCH'S    Sonnets,    Triumphs, 

and  other  Poems,  in  English  Verse.  With 
Life  by  Thomas  Campbell.  Portrait  and 
15  Steel  Engravings. 

PICKERING'S  History  of  the  Races 

of  Man,  and  their  Geographical  Distribu- 
tion ;  with  An  Analytical  Synopsis  of  , 
THE  Natural  History  of  Man.  By  Dr. 
Hall.     Map  of  the  World  and  12  Plates. 

With  the  Plates  coloured,  75.  6d. 

PICTORIAL      HANDBOOK     OF 

Modern  (xeography  on  a  Popular^  Plan. 
Compiled  from  the  best  Authorities,  English 
and  Foreign,  by  H.  G.  Bohn.  150  Wood- 
cuts and  51  Maps.     6s. 

With  the  Maps  coloured,  7^.  6d. 

Without  the  Maps,  3jr.  dd. 

POPE'S  Poetical  Works,  including 
Translations.  Edit.,  with  Notes,  by  R. 
Carruthers.     2  vols. 

Homer's    Iliad,    with    Introduction 

and  Notes  by  Rev.  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A. 
With  Flaxman's  Desig.ns.     N.  S. 

Homer's  Odyssey,  with  the  Battle 

OF  Frogs  and  Mice,  Hymns,  &c.,  by 
other  translators,  including  Chapman.  In- 
troduction and  Notes  by  J.  S.  Watson, 
M.A.    With  Flaxman's  Designs.     N.  S. 

Life,   including  many  of  his   Letters. 

By  R.  Carruthers.  Numerous  Illustrations. 

POTTERY  AND  PORCELAIN,  asd 

other  objects  of  Vertu.  Comprising  an 
Illustrated  Catalogue  of  the  Bernal  Col- 
lection, with  the  prices  and  names  of  the 
Possessors.  Also  an  Introductory  Lecture 
on  Pottery  and  Porcelain,  and  an  Engraved 
List  of  all  Marks  and  Monograms.  By 
H.  G.  Bohn.     Numerous  Woodcuts. 

With  coloured  Illustrations,  10^.  6d. 

PROUT'S  (Father)  Reliques.  Edited 
by  Rev.  F.  Rlahony.  Copyright  edition, 
with  the  Author's  last  corrections  and 
additions.  21  Etchings  by  D.  Maclise, 
R.A.     Nearly  600  pages.     5^.     N.  S. 

RECREATIONS  IN  SHOOTING.  With 
some  Account  of  the  Game  found  in  the 
British  Isles,  and  Directions  for  the  Manage- 
ment of  Dog  and  Gun.  By  '  Craven.'  62 
Woodcuts  and  9  Steel  Engravings  after 
A.  Cooper,  R.A. 


CLASSICAL  LIBRARY. 


13 


Jesuits 

^e.  Will 


leRact 


REDDING'S  History  and  Descrip- 
tions of  Wines,  Ancient  and  Modern.  20 
Woodcuts. 

RENNIE.  Insect  Architecture.  Re- 
vised by  Rev.  J.  G.  Wood,  ]\I.A.  186 
Woodcuts.     ^V.  6". 

ROBINSON  CRUSOE.  With  Memoir  of 
Defoe,  12  Steel  Engravings  and  74  Wood- 
cuts after  Stothard  and  Harvey. 

— —   Without  the  Engravings,  -^s.  6d. 

ROME  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CEN- 

tury.  An  Account  in  1817  of  the  Ruins  of 
the  Ancient  City,  and  Monuments  of  Modern 
Times.  By  C.  A.  Eaton.  34  Steel  En- 
gravings.    2  vols. 

SHARPE  (^.)    The  History  of  Egypt, 

from  the  Earliest  Times  till  the  Conquest 
by  the  Arabs,  a.d.  640.  2  Maps  and  up- 
wards of  400  Woodcuts.     2  vols.     N.  S. 

SOUTHEY'S  Life  of  Nelson.  With 
Additional  Notes,  Facsimiles  of  Nelson's 
Writing,  Portraits,  Plans,  and  50  Engrav- 
ings, after  Birket  Foster,  &c.     N.  S. 

STARLING'S  (Miss)  Noble  Deeds  of 

Women;  or.  Examples  of  Female  Courage, 
Fortitude,  and  Virtue.  With  14  Steel  Por- 
traits.    N.  S. 

STUART  and  REVETT'S  Antiqixities 

of  Athens,  and  other  Monuments  of  Greece  ; 
with  Glossary  of  Terms  used  in  Grecian 
Architecture.  71  Steel  Plates  and  numerous 
Woodcuts. 

SWEET'S  British^  Warblers.  ^s.—See 
Bechstein. 

TALES  OF  THE  GENII;  or,  the 
Delightful  Lessons  of  Horam,  the  Son  of 
Asmar.  Trans,  by  Sir  C.  Morrell.  Numer- 
ous Woodcuts. 

TASSO'S    Jerusalem    Delivered.    In 

English  Spenserian  Verse,  with  Life,  by 
J.  H.  Wiffen.  With  8  Engravings  and  24 
Woodcuts.     .V.  S. 


WALKER'S  Manly  Exercises;  con- 
taining Skating,  Riding,  Driving,  Hunting, 
Shooting,  .Sailing,  Rowing,  Swimming,  &:c. 
44  Engravings  and  numerous  Woodcuts. 

WALTON'S  Comp.lete  Angler,  or  the 

Contemplative  Man's  Recreation,  by  Izaak 
Walton  and  Charles  Cotton.  With  Me- 
moirs and  Notes  by  E.  Jesse.  Also  an 
Account  of  Fishing  Stations,  I'ackle,  &c. , 
by  H.  G.  Bohn.  Portrait  and  203  Wood- 
cuts.    N.  S. 

With  26  additional  Engravings  on  Steel, 

•]s.  6d. 

Lives  Of  Donne,  Wotton,  Hooker, 

&c.,  with  Notes.  A  New  Edition,  re- 
revised  by  A.  H.  Bullen,  with  a  Memoir 
of  Izaak  Walton  by  William  Dowling.  6 
Portraits,  6  Autograph  Signatures,  &c. 
N.S. 

W^ELLINGTON,  Life  of.  From  the 
Materials  of  Maxwell.  18  Steel  En- 
gravings. 

■ Victories  oi.—See  MaxivcU. 

WESTROPP  (H.  M.)  A  Handbook  of 

Archaeology,  Elgyptian,  Greek,  Etruscan, 
Roman.  By  H.  M.  Westropp.  Numerous 
Illustrations.     7^.  6d.     N.  S. 

WHITE'S   Natural   History  of  Sel- 

borne,  with  Observations  on  various  Parts 
of  Nature,  and  the  Naturalists'  Calendar. 
Sir  W.  Jardine.  Edit.,  with  Notes  and 
Memoir,  by  E.  Jesse.    40  Portraits.    N.  S. 

With  the  Plates  coloured,  -]$.  6d.  N.  S. 

YOUNG     LADY'S     BOOK,    The.     A 

Manual  of  Recreations,  Arts,  Sciences,  and 
Accomplishments.  1200  Woodcut  Illustra- 
tions,    "js.  6d. 

cloth  gilt,  gilt  edges,  gs. 


CLASSICAL    LIBRARY. 

Translations  from  the  Greek  and  Latin. 
95  Volss  at  ^s.  each,  excepting  those  marked  othevwise.     (23/.  *js.  per  set,) 


.ffiSCHYLUS,    The    Dramas    of.     In 

English  Verse  by  Anna   Swanwick.      3rd 
edition.     N.  S. 

The  Tragedies  of.     In  Prose,  with 

Notes  and  Introduction,  by  T.  A.  Buckley, 
B.A.     Portrait.     3^.  6d. 

AMMIANUS  MARCELLINUS.  His- 
tory of  Rome  during  the  Reigns  of  Con- 
stantius,  Julian,  Jovianus,Valentinian,  and 
Valens,  by  C.  D.  Yonge,  B.A.  Double 
volume.     TS.  6d. 


ANTONINUS     (M.     Aui'elius),     The 

Thoughts  of.  Translated  literally,  with 
Notes,  Biographical  Sketch,  and  Essay  on 
the  Philosophy,  by  George  Long,  M.A. 
2s.  6d.    N.  S. 

APULEIUS,  The  Works  of.  Com- 
prising the  Golden  Ass,  God  of  Socrates, 
Florida,  and  Discourse  of  Magic.  With 
a  Metrical  Version  of  Cupid  and  Psyche, 
and  Mrs.  Tighe's  Psyche.  Frontis- 
piece. 


14 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


\ 


ARISTOPHANES'  Comedies.    Trans., 

with  Notes  and  Extracts  from  Frere's  and 
other  Metrical  Versions,  l:y  W.  J.  Hickie. 
Portrait.     2  vols. 

ARISTOTLE'S  Nicomachean  Ethics. 

'Trans.,  with  Notes,  Analytical  Introduc- 
tion, and  Questions  for  Students,  by  Ven. 
Archdn.  Browne. 

Politics  and  Economics.    Trans., 

with  Notes,  Analyses,  and  Index,  by  E. 
Walford,  M.A.,  and  an  Essay  and  Life  by 
Dr.  Gillies. 

Metaphysics.     Trans.,  with   Notes, 

Analysis,  and  Examination  Questions,  by 
Rev.  John  H.  M'Mahon,  M.A. 

History  of  Animals.  In  Ten  Books. 

Trans.,  with  Notes  and  Index,  by  R. 
Cresswell,  I\I.A. 

Organon  ;  or.  Logical  Treatises,  and 

the  Introduction  of  Porphyry,  With  Notes, 
Analysis,  and  Introduction,  by  Rev.  O. 
F.  Owen,  ]\I.A.     2  vols.     3s.  6d.  each. 

■ Rhetoric  and  Poetics.  Trans,,  with 

Hobbes'  Analysis,  Exam.  Questions,  and 
Notes,  by  T,  i3uckley,  B.A,     Portrait. 

ATHEN.fflUS.     The   Deipnosophists ; 

or,  the  Banquet  of  the  Learned.  By  C.  D, 
Vonge,  B.A.  With  an  Appendix  of  Poeti- 
cal Fragments,     3  vols. 

ATLAS  of  Classical  Geography.    22 

large  Coloured  Maps.  With  a  complete 
Index.     Imp.  8vo.     7^".  dd. 

BION.— .Sc-r  Theocritus. 

CSSAR.      Commentaries    on    the 

(iallic  and  Civil  Wars,  with  the  Supple- 
nientarj-  Books  attributed  to  Hirtius,  in- 
cluding the  complete  Alexandrian,  African, 
and  Spanish  Wars.  Trans,  with  Notes. 
Portrait. 

CATULLUS,  Tibullus,  and  the  Vigil 

of  Venus.  Trans,  with  Notes  and  Bio- 
graphical Introduction.  To  which  are 
added.  Metrical  Versions  b}'  Lamb, 
(."irainger,  and  others.     Frontispiece, 

CICERO'S  Orations.  Trans,  by  C.  D. 
Vonge,  B.A.     4  vols. 

On  Oratory  and  Orators.    With 

Letters  to  Quintus  and  Brutus.  Trans., 
with  Notes,  by  Rev.  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A, 

On  the  Nature  of  the  Gods,  Divi- 
nation, Fate,  Laws,  a  Republic,  Consul- 
shi-p.  Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  C.  D.  Yonge, 
B.A, 

Academics,  De  Finibus,  and  Tuscu- 

lan  Questions,  By  C.  D.  Yonge,  B.A. 
With  Sketch  of  the  Greek  Philosophers 
mentioned  by  Cicero. 


1     CICERO'S  Ox&X\ox\&.— Continued. 

;    Offices;     or,     Moral     Duties.      Cato 

j  INIajor,  an  Essay  on  Old  Age  ;  Lselius,  an 
Essay  on    Friendship ;    Scipio's    Dream ; 

i  Paradoxes ;  Letter  tu  Quintus  on  Magis- 
trates. Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  C.  R.  Ed- 
monds.    Portrait.     3^-.  6d. 

!  DEMOSTHENES'  Orations.  Trans., 
;        with  Notes,   Arguments,  a  Chronological 

Abstract,   and   Appendices,    by  C.   Rann 

Kennedy.     5  vols, 

j    DICTIONARY  of  LATIN  and  GREEK 

Quotations  ;  including  Proverbs,  Maxims, 
Mottoes,  Law  Terms  and  Phrases,     With 

;        the  Quantities  marked,  and  English  Trans- 

j        lations, 

I    With  Index  Verborum  (622  pages),     6.S-. 

I    Index  Verborum  to  the  above,  with  the 

I  Quantities  and  Accents  marked  (56  pages), 
j        limp  cloth,     IS. 

I    DIOGENES   LAERTIUS.    Lives   and 

I  Opinions  of  the  Ancient  Philosophers. 
j        Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  C.  D,  Yonge,  B,A. 

EPICTETUS.      The    Discourses    of. 

1  With  the  Encheiridion  and  Fragments, 
With  Notes,  Life,  and  View  of  his  Philo- 

1        sophy,  by  George  Long,  M,A.     N.  S. 

i 

\  EURIPIDES.  Trans.,  with  Notes  and  In- 
troduction,  by  T.  A.  Buckley,  B.A.  Por- 
trait,    2  \ols, 

GREEK    ANTHOLOGY.      In    English 

1  Prose  by  G.  Purges,  M.A,  With  Metrical 
Versions  by  Bland,  Merivale,  Lord  Den- 
man,  S:c. 

GREEK  ROMANCES  of  Heliodorus, 

I>ongus,  and  Achilles  Tatius ;  viz,,  The 
Adventures  of  Theagenes  and  Chariclea ; 
Amours  of  Daphnis  and  Chloe  :  and  Loves 
of  Clitopho  and  Leucippe,  Trans.,  with 
!         Notes,  by  Rev   R,  Smith,  JNI.A. 

HERODOTUS.  Literally  trans,  by  Rev. 
Henry  Cary,  iNI.A,     Portrait. 

i    HE  SI  op,    CALLIMACHUS,    and 

!         Theognis.       In    Prose,    with    Notes    and 

Biographical   Notices   by  Rev.   J.   Banks, 

[         M.A,     Together  with   the   Metrical   Ver- 

'        sions  of  Hesiod,  by  Elton  ;    Callimachus, 

by  Tytler  ;  and  Theognis,  by  Frere. 

!  HOMER'S  Iliad.  In  English  Prose,  with 
j         Note,  by  T.  A,  Buckley,  B,A,     Portrait. 

Odyssey,     Hymns,     Epigrams,     and 

I  Battle  of  the  Frogs  and  Mice,  In  English 
j  Prose,  with  Notes  and  Memoir  by  T.  A. 
I         Buckley,  B.A. 

HORACE.  In  Prose  by  Smart,  with  Notes 
selected  by  '1".  A,  Buckley,  B.A.  Por- 
trail,     3.N-.  6d. 


CLASSICAL  LIBRARY. 


15 


JUSTIN,   CORNELIUS  NEPOS,  and 

Eutropius.  Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  Rev. 
J.  S.Watson,  M.A. 

JUVENAL,      PERSIUS,     SULPIGIA, 

and  Lucilius.  In  Prose,  with  Notes, 
Chronological  Tables,  Arguments,  bj--  L. 
Evans,  Al.A.  'I'o  which  is  added  the  Me- 
trical Version  of  Juvenal  awd  Persius  by 
Giftbrd.     Frontispiece. 

LIVY.  The  History  of  Rome.  Trans, 
by  Dr.  Spillan  and  others.  4  vols.  Por- 
trait. 

LUCAN'S  Pharsalia.  In  Prose,  with 
Notes  by  H.  T.  Riley. 

LUCRETIUS.  In  Prose,  with  Notes  and 
Biographical  Introduction  by  Re\-.  J.  S. 
Watson,  M.A.  To  which  is  added  the 
Metrical  Version  by  J.  M.  Good. 

MARTIAL'S  Epigrams,  complete.  In 
Prose,  with  Verse  Translations  selected 
from  English  Poets,  and  other  sources. 
Dble.  vol.  (670  pages).     7^-.  6d. 

MOSCHUS.— 5f^  Theocritus. 

OVID'S  Works,  complete.  In  Prose, 
with  Notes  and  Introduction.     3  vols. 

PHALARIS.    Bentley's  Dissertations 

upon  the  Epistles  of  Phalaris,  Themisto- 
cles,  .Socrates,  Euripides,  and  the  Fables 
of  /Esop.  With  Introduction  and  Notes 
by  Prof.  W.  Wagner,  Ph.D. 

PINDAR.  In  Prose,  with  Introduction 
and  Notes  by  Dawson  W.  Turner.  To- 
gether with  the  Metrical  Version  by  Abra- 
ham Moore.     Portrait. 

PLATO'S  "Works.  Trans.,  with  Intro- 
duction and  Notes.     6  vols. 

• Dialogues.    A  Summary  and  Analysis 

of.  With  Analytical  Index  to  the  Greek 
text  of  modern  editions  and  to  the  above 
translations,  by  A.  Day,  LL.D. 

PLAUTUS'S  Comedies.  In  Prose,  with 
Notes  and   Index  by  H.  T.   Riley,  B.A. 

2  vols. 

PLINY'S  Natural  History.  Trans., 
with  Notes,  by  J.  Bostock,  M.D.,  F.R.S., 
and  H.  T.  Riley,  P..A.     6  vols. 

PLINY.     The   Letters   of  Pliny  the 

Younger.  Melmoth's  Translation,  revised, 
with  Notes  and  short  Life,  by  Rev.  F.  C. 
T.  Bosanquet,  M.A, 


PLUTARCH'S     Morals.      Theosophical  \ 
Essays.  Trans,  by  C.  W.  King,  M.. A..  X.S. 

Lives.     Sec  page  6.  ] 

PROPERTIUS,  The  Elegies  of.    With  \ 

Notes,  Literally  translated  by  the  Rev.  P.  ■ 

J.  F.  Gantillon,   M.A.,  with  metrical  ver-  j 
sions  of  Select  Elegies  by  Nott  and  Elton. 

33-.  (id.  j 

QUINTILIAN'S  Institutes  of  Oratory.  | 

Trar.s.,     with     Notes     and      Biographical  1 
Notice,    by    Rev.    J.    S.    Watson,    M.A. 

2  vols.  I 


SALLUST,  FLORUS,  and  VELLEIUS 

Paterculus.     Trans.,  with   Notes  and   Bio- 
graphical Notices,  by  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A. 


SENECA. 


\,Prcf>aring. 


SOPHOCLES.    The  Tragedies  of.    In 

Prose,  with  Notes,  Arguments,  and  Intro-  ■ 

daction.     Portrait.  \ 

STRABO'S    Geography.      Trans.,  with  ■ 

Notes,  by  W.  Falconer,  M.A.,  and  H.  C.  ; 
Hamilton.     Copious  Index,  giving  Ancient 
and  Modern  Names.     3  vols. 

SUETONIUS'   Lives    of  the    Twelve 

Csesars   and    Lives   of  the    Grammarians. 

The  Translation  of  Thomson,  revised,  with  ■ 

Notes,  by  T.  Forester.  : 

TACITUS.      The  Works   of.      Trans.,  \ 

with  Notes.     2  vols.  1 

TERENCE  and  PH.EDRUS.     In  Eng-  i 

lish  Prose,  with  Notes  and  Arguments,  by  | 

H.    T.    Riley,    B.A.     To   which  is  added  | 

Smart's    Metrical     Version     of   Phaedrus.  . 

With  Frontispiece.  \ 

THEOCRITUS,     BION,     MOSCHUS,  \ 

and  Tyrtaeus.     In  Prose,  with  Notes  and  | 
Arguments,  by  Rev.  J.  Banks,  M.A.     To 

which  are  appended  the  Metrical  Ver-  j 

SIGNS  of  Chapman.    Portrait  of  Theocritus.  ' 

THUCYDIDES.    The  Peloponnesian  ! 

War.      Trans.,   with   Notes,  by   Rev.  H.  ' 

Dale.     Portrait.     2  vols.     3^.  (id.  each.  j 

TYRT.flBUS.— .S-^t;  Theocritus.  j 

VIRGIL.     The  Works  of.      In  Prose,  j 

with  Notes  by  Davidson.      Revised,  with  ; 

additional  Notes  and  Biographical  Notice,  I 

by  T.  A.  Buckley,  B.A.     Portrait.     3^.  (id.  I 

XENOPHON'S     Works.      Trans.,   with  j 

Notes,  by  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A.,  and  others.  , 

Portrait.     In  3  vols.  j 


BONN'S  LIBRARIES. 


COLLEGIATE     SERIES. 

10  Vols,  at  ^s.  each.     (2/.  los.  per  set.) 


DANTE.  The  Inferno.  Prose  Trans., 
with  the  Text  of  the  Origuial  on  the  same 
page,  and  Explanatory  Notes,  by  John 
A.  Carlyle,  M.D.     Portrait.     .V.  6-. 

The  Purgatorio.    Prose  Trans.,  with 

the  Original  on  the  same  page,  and  Ex- 
planatory Notes,  by  W.  S.  Dugdale.    ^V.  S. 

NEW  TESTAMENT  (The)  in  Greek. 

Griesbach's  Text,  with  the  Readings  of 
Mill  and  Scholz  at  the  foot  of  the  page,  and 
Parallel  References  in  the  margin.  Also  a 
Critical  Introduction  and  Chronological 
Tables.  Two  Fac-similes  of  Greek  Manu- 
scripts.    650  pages,     -^s.  6d. 

or  bound  up  with  a  Greek  and  English 

Lexicon  to  the  New  Testament  (250  pages 
additional,  making  in  all  900J.     55. 

The   Lexicon    may  be  had  separatelj', 
price  2S. 

DOBREE'S  Adversaria.  (Notes  on  the 
Greek  and  Latin  Classics.)  Edited  by  the 
late  Prof.  Wagner.     2  vois. 


DONALDSON  (Dr.)    The  Theatre  of 

the  Greeks.  With  Supplementary  Treatise 
on  the  Language,  Metres,  and  Prosody  of 
the  Greek  Dramatists.  Numerous  Illus- 
trations and  3  Plans.  By  J.  W.  Donald- 
son, D.D.     N.S. 

KEIGHTLEY'S  (Thomas)  Mythology 

of  Ancient  Greece  and  Italj'.  Revised  by 
Leonhaxd    Schmitz,     Ph.D.,    LL.D.      12 

Plates.     iV.  6\ 

HERODOTUS,    Notes    on.     Original 

and  Selected  from  the  best  Commentators. 
By  D.  W.  Turner,  M.A.     Coloured  Map. 

Analysis  and  Snnimary  of,  with 

a  Synchronistical  Table  of  E\>ents — Tables 
of  Weights,  Measures,  Money,  and  Dis- 
tances—  an  Outline  of  the  History  and 
Geography — and  the  Dates  completed  from 
Gaisford,  Baehr,  &c.     By  J.  T.  Wheeler. 

THUCYDIDES.      An    Analysis    and 

.Summary  of.  With  Chronological  Table 
of  Events,  &c.,  by  J.  T.  Wheeler. 


SCIENTIFIC    LIBRARY. 

57  Vols,  at  ^s.  each,  excepting  those  vmrlced  otherwise.     (15/.  2s.  per  set.) 


AGASSIZ    and    GOULD.    Outline  of 

Comparative  Physiology  touching  the 
Structure  and  Development  of  the  Races 
of  Animals  living  and  extinct.  For  Schools 
and  Colleges.  Enlarged  by  Dr.  Wright. 
W^ith  Index  and  300  Illustrative  Woodcuts. 

BOLLEY'S    Manual    of   Technical 

Analysis ;  a  Guide  for  the  Testing  and 
Valuation  of  the  various  Natural  and 
Artificial  Substances  employed  in  the  Arts 
and  Domestic  Economy,  founded  on  the 
work  of  Dr.  Bolley.  Edit,  by  Dr.  Paul. 
IOC  Woodcuts. 

BRIDGEWATER  TREATISES. 

—-  Bell  (Sir  Charles)  on  the  Hand ; 

its  Mechanism  and  Vital  Endowments,  as 
evincing  Design.  Preceded  by  an  Account 
of  the  Author's  Discoveries  in  the  Nervous 
System  by  A.  Shaw.    Numerous  Woodcuts. 

Kirby  on   the  History,  Habits, 

and  Instincts  of  Animals.  With  Notes  by 
T.  Rymer  Jones.     100  Woodcuts.     2  vols. 

Kidd  on  the  Adaptation  of  Ex- 
ternal Nature  to  the  Physical  Condition  of 
Man,  principally  with  reference  to  the 
Supply  of  his  Wants  and  the  Exercises  of 
his  Intellectual  Faculties.     35.  6d. 


BRIDGEWATER    TREATISES.— 

Contintced. 
Whewell's    Astronomy    and 

General  Physics,  considered  with  reference 
to  Natural  Theology.  Portrait  of  the  Earl 
of  Bridgewater.     3^.  6d. 

Chalmers  on  the  Adaptation  of 

External  Nature  to  the  Moral  and  Intel- 
lectual Constitution  of  Man.  With  Memoir 
by  Rev.  Dr.  Gumming.     Portrait. 

Front's  Treatise  on  Chemistry, 

Meteorology,  and  the  Function  of  Diges- 
tion, with  reference  to  Natural  Theology. 
Edit,  by  Dr.  J.  W.  Griffith.     2  Maps. 

Buckland's  Geology  and  Miner- 
alogy. With  Additions  by  Prof.  Owen, 
Prof.  Phillips,  and  R.  Brown.  Memoir  of 
Buckland.  Portrait.  2  vols.  15^.  Vol.  I. 
Text.  Vol.  11.  90  large  plates  with  letter- 
press. 

• Roget's  Animal   and  Vegetable 

Physiology-.  463  Woodcuts.  2  vols.  6s. 
each. 

BROWNE.    Manual  of  Geology.    By 

A.  J.  Jukes  Browne.  With  numerous 
Diagrams  and  Illustrations,  6s. 


SCIENTIFIC  LIBRARY. 


17 


tie  of 


Table 


table 


CARPENTER'S  (Dr.  "W.  B.)  Zoology. 

A  Systematic  View  of  the  Structure,  Ha- 
bits, Instincts,  and  Uses  of  the  principal 
Families  of  the  Animal  Kingdom,  and  of 
the  chief  Forms  of  Fossil  Remains.  Re- 
vised by  \V.  S.  Dallas,  F.L.S.  Numerous 
Woodcuts.     2  vols.     6^.  each. 

Mechanical  Philosophy,  Astro- 
nomy, and  Horology-.  A  Popular  Expo- 
sition.    181  Woodcuts. 

Vegetable  Physiology  and  Sys- 
tematic Botany.  A  complete  Introduction 
to  the  Knowledge  of  Plants.  Revised  by 
E.  Lankester,  M.D.,  &c.  Numerous 
Woodcuts.     6^. 

Animal  Physiology.  Revised  Edi- 
tion.    300  Woodcuts,     bs. 

CHEVREUL  on  Colour.  Contahiing 
the  Principles  of  Harmony  and  Contrast 
of  Colours,  and  their  Application  to  the 
Arts  ;  including  Painting,  Decoration, 
Tapestries,  Carpets,  Mosaics,  Glazing, 
Staining,  Calico  Printing,  Letterpress 
Printing,  Map  Colouring,  Dress,  Land- 
scape and  Flower  Gardenmg,  &c.  Trans, 
by  C.  Martel.     Several  Plates. 

With  an  additional  series  of  16  Plates 

in  Colours,  -js.  6d. 

ENNEMOSER'S    History   of  Magic. 

Trans,  by  W.  Howltt.  With  an  Appendix 
of  the  most  remarkable  and  best  authenti- 
cated Stories  of  Apparitions,  Dreams, 
Second  Sight,  Table-Tuming,  and  Spirit- 
Rapping,  &c.     2  vols. 

HIND'S  Introduction  to  Astronomy. 

With  Vocabulary  of  the  Terms  in  present, 
use.     Numerous  Woodcuts.     3.?.  6d.    N.S, 

HOGG'S  (Jabez)  Elements  of  Experi- 
mental and  Natural  Philosophy.  Being 
an  Easy  Introduction  to  the  Study^  of 
Mechanics,  Pneumatics,  Hydrostatics, 
Hydraulics,  Acoustics,  Optics,  Caloric, 
Electricity,  Voltaism,  and  Magnetism. 
400  Woodcuts. 

HUMBOLDT'S  Cosmos;   or,  Sketch 

of  a  Physical  Description  of  the  Universe. 
Trans,  by  E.  C.  Otte,  B.  H.  Paul,  and 
W.  S.  Dallas,  F.L.S.  Portrait.  5  vols. 
35.  6d.  each,  excepting  vol.  v.,  55. 

•  Personal  Narrative  of  his  Travels 

in  America  during  the  years  1799-1804. 
Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  T.  Ross.     3  vols. 

Views  of  Nature ;  or,  Contem- 
plations of  the  Sublime  Phenomena  of 
Creation,  with  Scientffic  Illustrations. 
Trans,  by  E.  C.  Otte. 

HUNT'S  (Robert)  Poetry  of  Science  ; 

or.  Studies  of  the  Physical  Phenomena  of 
Nature.  By  Robert  Hunt,  Professor  at 
the  School  of  Mines. 


JOYCE'S     Scientific    Dialogues.     A 

Familiar    Introduction   to    the    Arts    and 
Sciences.     For  Schools  and  Young  People. 
Numerous  Woodcuts. 
Introduction    to   the   Arts   and 

Sciences,  for  Schools  and  Young  People. 
Divided  into  Lessons  with  Examination 
Questions.     Woodcuts.     35.  6d. 

JUKES-BROWNE'S  Student's  Hand- 
book of  Physical  Geology.  By  A.  J. 
Jukes-Browne,  of  the  Geological  Survey  of 
England.  With  numerous  Diagrams  and 
Illustrations,  65-.     N.S. 

KNIGHT'S   (Charles)   Knowledge  is 

Power.      A   Popular   Manual   of  Political 
Economj'. 
LECTURES    ON    PAINTING    by    the 

Royal  Academicians,  Barry,  Opie,  Fuseli. 
With  Introductory  Essay  and  Notes  by 
R.  Wornum.     Portrait  of  Fuseli. 

LILLY.    Introduction  to  Astrology. 

With  a  Grammar  of  Astrology  and  Tables 
for  calculating  Nativities,  by  Zadkiel. 

MANTELL'S  (Dr.)  Geological  Ex- 
cursions through  the  Isle  of  Wight  and 
along  the  Dorset  Coast.  Numerous  Wood- 
cuts and  Geological  Map. 

Medals   of  Creation ;   or,  First 

Lessons  in  Geology  :  including  Geological 
Excursions.  Coloured  Plates  and  several 
hundred  Woodcuts.     2  vols.  js.  6d.  each. 

Petrifactions  and  their  Teach- 
ings. Handbook  to  the  Organic  Remains 
in  the  British  Musexm.  Numerous  Wood- 
cuts.    6s. 

Wonders    of    Geology ;     or,    a 

Familiar  Exposition  of  Geological  Pheno- 
mena. A  coloured  Geological  Map  of 
England,  Plates,  and  200  Woedcuts.  2 
vols.  75.  6d.  each. 

MORPHY'S  Games  of  Chess,  being 
the  Matches  and  best  Games  played  by  the 
American  Champion,  with  explanatory  and 
analytical  Notes  by  J.  Lowenthal.  With 
short  Memoir  and  Portrait  of  Morphy. 

SCHOtrW'S  Earth,  Plants,  and  Man. 

Popular  Pictures  of  Nature.  And  Ko- 
bell's  Sketches  from  the  Mineral  Kingdom. 
Trans,  by  A.  Henfrey,  F.R.S.  Coloured 
Map  of  the  Geography  of  Plants. 

SMITH'S  (Pye)  Geology  and  Scrip- 
ture ;  or,  the  Relation  between  the  Scriptures 
and  Geological  Science.     With  Memoir. 

STANLEY'S    Classified   Synopsis  of 

the  Principal  Painters  of  the  Dutch  and 
Flemish  Schools,  including  an  Account  of 
some  of  the  early  German  Masters.  By 
George  Stanley. 
STAUNTON'S  Chess-Player's  Hand- 
book. A  Popular  and  Scientific  Intro- 
duction to  the  Game,  with  numerous  Dia- 
grams and  Coloured  Frontispiece.     N.S. 


iS 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


STAJTSi'TO'N.—Cojitmned. 

Chess  Praxis.     A  Supplement  to  the 

Chess-player's  Handbook.  Containing  the 
most  important  modern  Improvements  in 
the  Openings  ;  Code  of  Chess  Laws  ;  and 
n  Selection  of  Morphy's  Games.  Annotated. 
636  pages.     Diagrams.     6s. 

Chess-Player's    Companion. 

Comprising  a  Treatise  on  Odds,  Collection 
of  Match  Games,  including  the  French 
ISlatch  with  M.  St.  Amant,  and  a  Selection 
of  Original  Problems.  Diagrams  and  Co- 
loured Frontispiece. 

Chess    Tournament     of    1851. 

A  Collection  of  Games  played  at  this  cele- 
brated assemblage.  With  Introduction 
and  Notes.     Numerous  Diagrams. 


STOCKHARDT'S      Experimental 

Chemistry-.  A  Handbook  for  the  Study 
of  the  Science  by  simple  Experiments- . 
Edit,  by  C.  W.  Heaton,  F.C.S.  Ni- 
merous  Woodcuts.     A''.  S. 

URE'S  (Dr.  A.)  Cotton  Manufacture^ 

of  Great    Britain,   systematically   invest: 
gated  ;   with  an  Introductory*  View  of  it- 
Comparative  State  in  Foreign  Countrie.-. 
Revised  by  P.  L.  Simmonds.     150  Illus- 
trations.    2  vols. 

Philosophy    of   Manufactures,^ 

or  an  Exposition  of  the  Scientific,  Mora! 
and  Commercial  Economy  of  the  Factory 
System  of   Great    Britain.      Revised    b\- 
P.    L.    Simmonds.      Numerous    Figure^. 
800  pages,     -js.  6d. 


ECONOMICS   AND    FINANCE. 

GILBART'S  History,  Principles,  and  Practice  of  Banking.    Revised  to  i33i 
A.  S.  Michie,  of  the  Royal  Bank  of  Scotland.     Portrait  of  Gilbart.     2  vols.     lo^.     ^V. 


REFERENCE    LIBRARY. 

27  Volumes  at  'Various  Prices.     {^L  ^s. per  set.) 


BOHNS     Dictionary     of     Poetical 

Quotations.    P'ourth  Edition.     6^. 

BUCHANAN'S  Dictionary  of  Science 

and  Technical  Terms  used  in  Philosophy, 
Literature,  Professions,  Commerce,  Arts, 
and  Trades.  By  W.  H.  Buchanan,  with 
v^upplement.   Edited  by  Jas.  A.  Smith,  bs. 

BLAIR'S     Chronological     Tables. 

Comprehending  t-he  Chronology  and  His- 
tory- of  the  World,  from  the  Earliest  Times 
to  the  Russian  Treaty  of  Peace,  April  1856. 
ByJ.W.  Rosse.     800  pages.     \os. 

Index    of   Dates.      Comprehending 

the  principal  Facts  in  the  Chronologj"  and 
History  of  the  World,  from  the  Earliest  to 
the  Present,  alphabetically  arranged ;  being 
Ci  complete  Index  to  the  foregoing.  Bj- 
J.  W.  Rosse.     2  vols.  5^.  each. 

BOHN'S   Dictionary  of  Quotations 

i'tom  the  English  Poets.     4th  and  cheaper 

Edition.     6s. 

BUCHANAN'S  Dictionary  of  Science 

and  Technical  Terms.  With  Supplement. 
820  pp.     6s. 

CLARK'S    (Hvigh)    Introduction    to 

Heraldry-.  Revised  by  J.  R.  Planche.  55. 
950  Illustrations. 

With  the  Illitstrations  coloured y   155-. 

N.  S. 


CHRONICLES  OF  THE  TOMBS.     A 

Select  Collection  of  Epitaphs,  with  Essay 
on  Epitaphs  and  Observations  on  Sepiil 
chral  Antiquities.  By  T.  J.  Pettigrev, , 
F.R.S.,  F.S.A.     5^. 

COINS,  Manual  of.— 6"^^  Hnuiphrcys. 

DATES,  Index  of. —Sec  Blair. 

DICTIONARY  of  Obsolete  and  Pio- 

vincial  English.  Containing  Words  fron: 
English  Writers  previous  to  the  19th: 
Century.  By  Thomas  Wright,  M.A., 
F.S.A.,  &c.     2  vols.  55-.  each. 

EPIGRAMMATISTS  (The).  A  Selec- 
tion from  the  Epigrammatic  Literature  ot 
Ancient,  Mediaeval,  and  Modern  Time-. 
With  Introduction,  Notes,  Observation.-, 
Illustrations,  an  Appendix  on  Works  con- 
nected with  Epigrammatic  Literature, 
by  Rev.  H.  Dodd,  M.A.     6^.     N.  S. 

GAMES,  Handbook  of.  Comprising 
Treatises  on  above  40  Games  of  Chance 
Skill,  and  Manual  Dexterity,  including 
Whist,  Billiards,  &c.  _  Edit,  by  Henry  G. 
Bohn.     Numerous  Diagrams.     $$.    K.  S. 

HUMPHREYS'     Coin    Collectors^ 

Manual.  An  Historical  Account  of  the 
Progress  of  Coinage  from  the  Eariiest 
Time,  by  H.  N.  Humphreys.  140  Illu:?- 
trations.     2  vols.  5,?.  each.     A".  6". 


NO  VELISTS'  JJBKA R  \  \ 


19 


2.0WNDES'  Bibliographer's  Manual 

of  English  Literature.  Containiii":  an  Ac- 
count of  Rare  and  Curious  Books  pub- 
lished in  or  relating  to  Great  Britain  and 
Ireland,  from  the  Invention  of  Printing, 
with  Biographical  Notices  and  Prices, 
by  W.  T.  Lowndes.  Parts  I.-X.  (A  to  Z), 
ii^.  6if.  each.  Part  XI.  (Appendix  Vol.), 
ss.  Or  the  11  parts  in  4  vols.,  half 
morocco,  2/.  2s. 

MEDICINE,  Handbook  of  Domestic, 

Popularlj'  Arranged.     By  Dr.  H.  Davies. 

700  pages.     5^. 

NOTED      NAMES      OF      FICTION. 

Dictionary'  of.  Including  also  Familiar 
Pseudonyms,  Surnames  bestowed  on  Emi- 
nent -Men,  &c.  By  W.  A.  Wheeler,  M.A. 
^s.     X.S. 


POLITICAL     CYCLOPAEDIA.      A 

Dictionary  of  Political,  Constitutional, 
Statistical,  and  Forensic  Knowledge  ; 
forming  a  Work  of  Reference  on  subjects 
of  Civil  Administration,  Political  Economy, 
Finance,  Commerce,  Laws,  and  Social 
Relations.     4  vols.  3^-.  6d.  each. 

PROVERBS,  Handbook  of.  Con- 
taining an  entire  Republication  of  Ray's 
Collection,  with  Additions  from  Foreign 
Languages  and  Sayings,  Sentences, 
."Maxims,  and  Phrases,  collected  by  H.  G. 
Bohn.     5^. 

A  Polyglot  of  Foreign.  Com- 
prising I'rench,  Italian,  German,  Dutcli, 
Spanish,  Portuguese,  and  Danish.  With 
English  Translations.     5^-. 

SYNONYMS  and    ANTONYMS;    or. 

Kindred  Words  and  their  Opposites,  Col- 
lected   and    Contrasted    by    Ven.    C.    J. 
Smith,  M.A.     5:?.     N.  S. 
WRIGHT  {'Th..)-Sce  Dictionary. 


NOVELISTS'    LIBRARY. 


10  Volumes  at  y.  6d.  eacli,  excepting  those  inaj-ked  otherwise,     (r/.  i2is.  fer  set.) 


BURNEY'S  Evelina  ;  or,  a  Young 
Lady's  Entrance  into  the  World.  By  F. 
Eumey  (Mme.  D'Arblay).  With  Intro- 
duction and  Notes  by  A.  R.  Ellis,  Author 
of 'Sylvestra,'  &c.     X.  S. 

■    Cecilia.       With     Introduction    and 

Notes  by  A.  R.  Ellis.     2  vols.     N.  S. 

FIELDING'S    Joseph    Andrews  and 

his  Friend  Mr.  Abraham  Adams.  With 
Roscoe's  Biography.  Cruikshank's  Ilhts- 
trations.     N.  S. 

- — -  History  of  Tom  Jones,  a  Found- 
ling. Roscoe's  Edition.  Cruikshank's 
UlustraiioHs.     2  vols.     N.  S. 


TlEIAyJNG.—Ccniim^ed. 

■ Amelia.      Roscoe's  Edition,  revised, 

Cruiksiiank's  Illitstrations.     5,?.     N.  S. 


Visconti.      Trans. 


GROSSI'S    Marco 

by  A.  F.  D.     N.  S. 

1    MANZONL     The   Betrothed:    being   I 
;        a     Translation    of    '  I     Promessi     Sposi.' 
Numerous  Woodcuts,     i  vol.  (732  pages), 
i        Ss.     y-S.  I 

j    STOWE  (Mrs.  H.  B.)     Uncle  Tom's   i 

Cabin  ;  or.  Life  among  the  Lowly.     S  full-    | 

I        page  Illustrations.     JV.  S.  1 


ARTISTS'    LIBRARY. 

5  Volumes  at  Various  Prices,     (i/.  8^.  6d.  per  set.) 


EELL  (Sir  Charles).     The  Anatomy 

and  Philosophy  of  Expression,  as  Con- 
nected with  the  Fine  Arts,     s^-     -'^^'  -S. 

DEMMIN.      History   of  Arms   and 

Armour  from  the  Earliest  Period.  By 
Auguste  Demmin.  Trans,  by  C.  C. 
Black,  M.A.,  Assistant  Keeper,  S.  K. 
Museum.    1900  Illustrations,    js.  6d.   N.  S. 

FLAXMAN.    Lectures  on  Sculpture.    I 

With  Three  Addresses  to  the  R.A.  by  Sir    i 


R.  Westmacott,  R.A.,  and  Memoir  of 
Flaxman.  Portrait  and  53  Plates.    6i-.  A'.^". 

LEONARDO    DA    VINCI'S    Treatise 

on  Painting.  Trans,  by  J.  F.  Rigaud,  R.A. 
With  a  Life  and  an  Account  of  his  Works 
by  J.  W.  Brown.  Numerous  Plates,  ^i•. 
N.S. 

PLANCHE'S    History    of    British 

Costume,  from  the  Earliest  Time  to  the 
19th  Century.  By  J.  R.  Planche.  400 
Illustrations.      j.    N.  S. 


(  20  ) 

BOHN'S   CHEAP   SERIES. 

PRICE  ONE  SHILLING  EACH. 


A  Series  of  Complete  Stories  or  Essays,  mostly  reprinted  from  Vols. 

in  Bohn^s  Libraries,  and  7ieatly  boimd  iii  stiff  paper  cover, 

with  cut  edges,  suitable  for  Railway  Reading, 


ASCHAM  {ROGER).— 

SCHOLEMASTER.    By  Professor  Mayor. 

CARPENTER  {DR.   Jr.  B.).— 

PHYSIOLOGY     OF     TEMPERANCE     AND     TOTAL    AB- 

STLNENCE. 

EMERSON.— 

ENGLAND  AND  ENGLISH  CHARACTERISTICS.    Lectures 
on  the  Race,  Ability,  Manners,  Truth,  Character,  Wealth,  Religion,  &c.  &c. 

NATURE  :  An  Essay.     To  which  are  added  Orations,  Lectures^ 
and  Addresses. 

REPRESENTATIVE  MEN  :  Seven  Lectures  on  Plato,  Swe- 
DENBORG,  Montaigne,  Shakespeare,  Napoleon,  and  Goethe. 

TWENTY  ESSAYS  on  Various  Subjects. 
THE  CONDUCT  OF  LIFE. 

FRANKLIN  {BENfAMlN).— 

AUTOBIOGRAPHY.    Edited  by  J.  Sparks. 

HAWTHORN.E  {NATHANIEL).— 

TWICE-TOLD  TALES.     Two  Vols,  in  One. 

SNOW  IMAGE,  and  other  Tales. 

SCARLET  LETTER. 

HOUSE  WITH  THE  SEVEN  GABLES. 

TRANSFORMATION  ;  or  the  Marble  Fawn.     Two  Parts. 

HAZLITT  {W.).— 

TABLE-TALK  :  Essays  on  Men  and  Manners.     Three  Parts. 

PLAIN    SPEAKER  :    Opinions   on  Books,    Men,    and   Things. 
Three  Parts. 

LECTURES  ON  THE  ENGLISH  COMIC  WRITERS. 

LECTURES  ON  THE  ENGLISH  POETS. 


BOHN'S  CHEAP  SEKIES.  21     ; 

HAZLITT  ( W.).—Contimicd.  I 

LECTURES    ON    THE    CHARACTERS    OF    SHAKE-  \ 

SPEARE'S  PLAYS.  | 

LECTURES   ON   THE   LITERATURE  OF   THE  AGE  OF    ! 

ELIZABETH,  chiefly  Dramatic.  j 

IRVING  {WASHINGTON).—  I 

LIFE  OF  MOHAMMED.     With  Portrait.  ! 

LIVES  OF  SUCCESSORS  OF  MOHAMMED.  ; 

LIFE  OF  GOLDSMITH. 

SKETCH-BOOK. 

TALES  OF  A  TRAVELLER. 

TOUR  ON  THE  PRAIRIES. 

CONQUESTS  OF  GRANADA  AND  SPAIN.     Two  Parts. 

LIFE  AND  VOYAGES  OF  COLUMBUS.     Two  Parts. 

COMPANIONS    OF    COLUMBUS:    Their  Voyages  and  Dis- 
coveries. 

ADVENTURES  OF  CAPTAIN  BONNEVILLE  in  the  Rocky 

Mountains  and  the  Far  West. 
KNICKERBOCKER'S  HISTORY  OF  NEW  YORK,  from  the 

Begiiining  of  the  World  to  the  End  of  the  Dutch  Dynasty. 
TALES  OF  THE  ALHAMBRA. 

CONQUEST     OF    FLORIDA    UNDER    HERNANDO    DE 

SOTO. 
ABBOTSFORD  AND  NEWSTEAD  ABBEY.  ] 

SALMAGUNDI;     or,    The    Whim -Whams    and    Opinions    of  | 
Launcelot  Langstaff,  Esq.  i 

BRACEBRIDGE  HALL  ;  or.  The  Humourists.  ! 

ASTORIA  ;  or,  Anecdotes  of  an  Enterprise  beyond  the  Rocky 
Mountains. 

WOLFERT'S  ROOST,  and  Other  Tsles. 
LAMB  {CHARLES).— 

ESSAYS  OF  ELIA.     With  a  Portrait. 

LAST  ESSAYS  OF  ELIA. 

ELIANA.     With  Biographical  Sketch.  ^ 

MARR  YA  T  ( CAPTAIN).  \ 

PIRATE  AND  THE  THREE  CUTTERS.     With  a  Memoir  of  | 

the  Author.  i 


(  22  ) 

The  only  authorised  Edition  ;  no  others  published  in  England  C07itai?i 

the  Derivations  and  Etymological  A'otes  of  Dr.  Mahn^  who 

devoted  several  years  to  this  portion  of  the  Work. 

^WEBSTER'S     DICTIONARY 

OF    THE    ENGLISH    LANGUAGE. 

Thoroughly  revised  and  improved  byCHAUNCEY  A.  Goodrich,  D.D.,  LL.D., 
and  Noah  Porter,  D.D.,  of  Yale  College. 


THE    GUINEA    DICTIONARY. 

New  Edition  [1880],  with  a  Supplement  of  upv.ards  of  4600  New  Words  and 

Meanings. 
1628  Pages.     3000  Illusti'ations. 
The  features  of  this   volume,   which   render   it    perhaps   the   most  useful 
Dictionary  for  general  reference  extant,  as  it  is  undoubtedly  one  of  the  cheapest 
books  ever  published,  are  as  follows  : — 

1.  Completeness. — It  contains  114,000  words — more  by  10,000  than  any 

other  Dictionary  ;  and  these  are,  for  the  most  part,  unusual  or  technical 
terms,  for  the  explanation  of  which  a  Dictionary  is  most  wanted. 

2.  Accuracy  of  Definition. — In  the  present  edition  all  the  definitions  have 

been  carefully  and  methodically  analysed  by  W.  G.  Webster,  the  Rev.  C. 
Goodrich.  Prof.  Lyman,  Prof.  Whitney,  r.nd  Prof.  Gilman,  under  the 
superintendence  of  Prof.  Goodrich. 

3.  Scientific  and   Technical  Terms. — In   order  to   secure   the  utmost 

completeness  and  accuracy  of  definition,  this  department  has  been  sub- 
divided among  eminent  scholars  and  experts,  including  Prof.  Dana,  Prof. 
Lyman,  &c. 

4.  Etymology. — The  eminent  philologist,  Dr.  C.  F.  Mahn,  has  devoted  five 

years  to  completing  this  department. 

o.  The  Orthography  is  based,  as  far  as  possible,  on  Fixed  Principles.     In 
all  cases  of  dotibi  an  alternative  spelling  is  given. 

6.  Pronunciation. — This  has  been  entrusted  to  Mr.  W.  G.  Webster  and  Mr. 

Wheeler,  assisted  by  other  scholars.  The  pronunciation  of  each  word  is 
indicated  by  typographical  signs  printed  at  the  bottom  of  each  page. 

7.  The  Illustrative  Citations. — No  labour  has  been  spared  to  embody 

such  quotations  from  standard  authors  as  may  throw  light  on  the  defini- 
tions, or  possess  any  special  interest  of  thought  or  language. 

8.  The  Synonyms. — These  are  subjoined  to  the  words  to  which  they  belong, 

and  are  very  complete. 

9.  The  Illustrations,  which  exceed  3000,  are  inserted,  not  for  the  sake  of 

ornament,  but  to  elucidate  the  meaning  of  words. 

Cloth,  2is.  ;  half-bound  in  calf,  30^'.  ;  calf  or  half  russia,  31^-.  (xi.',  russia,  2/. 


To  he  obtained  tlu-ough  all  Bookselkrs, 


H 


(    23    ) 

WEBSTER'S     DICTIONARY. 


*  Seventy  years  passed  before  Johnson  was  followed  by  Webster,  an 

American  writer,  who  faced  the  task  of  the  English  Dictionary  with  a 

full   appreciation    of   its    requirements,    leading    to    better    practical 

results.'    .     .     . 

j         '  His  laborious  comparison  of  twenty  languages,  though  never  pub- 

I  lished,  bore  fruit  in  his  own  mind,  and  his  training  placed  him  both  in 

I  knowledge  and  judgment  far  in  advance  of  Johnson  as  a  philologist. 

I  Webster's  American  Dictionary  of  the  English  Language  was  pub- 

j  lished    in   1828,  and  of  course  appeared  at  once  in  England,  where 

I  successive  re-editing  Jias  yet  kept  it  in  t/ie  highest  place  as  a  practical 

!  Dictionary.'' 

I        *  The  acceptance  of  an  American  Dictionary  in  England  has  itself 

I  had  immense  effect  in  keeping  up  the  community  of  speech,  to  break 

!  which   would  be  a  grievous  harm,   not  to  English-speaking  nations 

alone,  but  to  mankind.     The  result  of  this  has  been  that  the  common 

Dictionary  must  suit  both  sides  of  the  Atlantic'     .     .     . 

'The  good  average  business-like  character  of  Webster's  Dictionary, 
both  in  style  and  matter,  made  it  as  distinctly  suited  as  Johnson's  was 
distinctly  unsuited  to  be  expanded  and  re-edited  by  other  hands. 
Professor  Goodrich's  edition  of  1847  is  not  much  more  than  enlarged 
and  amended  ;  but  other  revisions  since  have  so  much  novelty  of  plan 
as  to  be  described  as  distinct  works.'     .     .     . 

'  The  American  revised  Webster's  Dictionary  of  1864,  published  in 
America  and  England,  is  of  an  altogether  higher  order  than  these  last 
[The  London  Imperial  and  Student's].  It  bears  on  its  title-page  the 
names  of  Drs.  Goodrich  and  Porter,  but  inasmuch  as  its  especial  im- 
provement is  in  the  etymological  department,  the  care  of  which  was 
committed  to  Dr.  Mahn  of  Berlin,  we  prefer  to  describe  it  in  short  as 
the  Webster-Mahn  Dictionary.  Many  other  literary  men,  among  them 
Professors  Whitney  and  Dana,  aided  in  the  task  of  compilation  and 
revision.  On  consideration  it  seems  that  the  editors  and  contributors 
have  gone  far  toward  improving  Webster  to  the  utmost  that  he  will 
bear  improvement.  The  vocabulary  has  become  almost  complete  as 
regards  usual  words,  while  the  definitions  keep  throughout  to  IVebster's 
simple  careful  style,  and  the  derivations  are  assigned  with  the  aid  of 
good  moderti  authorities.'' 

'  On  the  whole,  the  Webster-Mahn  Dictionary  as  it  stands  is  most 
respectable,  and  certainly  the  best  Practical  English  Dic- 
tionary extant.'— From  the  Quarterly  J^eview,  Oct.  1873. 


London  :  G.  BELL  &  SONS,  York  Street,  Covent  Garden. 


(  24  ) 

New  Edition,  with  a  New  Biographical  Supplement  of  upwards  of  900  Names. 

WEBSTER'S  COMPLETE  DICTIONARY 

AND  BOOK  OF  LITERARY  REFERENCE. 

1919  Pages.    3000  Illustrations. 

Besides  the  matter  comprised  in  the  Webster's  Guinea  Dictionary,  this 
volume  contains  the  following  Appendices,  which  will  show  that  no  pains  have 
been  spared  to  make  it  a  complete  Literary  Reference-book  : — 

A  Brief  History  of  the  English  Language.     By  Prof.  James  Hadley. 

Principles  of  Pronunciation.  By  Prof.  Goodrich  and  W.  A.  Wheeler,  M.A, 
Including  a  Synopsis  of  Words  differently  pronounced  by  different  authorities. 

A  Short  Treatise  on  Orthography.  By  A.  W.  Wright.  Including  a  com- 
plete List  of  Words  that  are  spelt  in  two  or  more  ways. 

Vocabulary  of  Noted  Names  of  Fiction.  By  W.  A.  Wheeler,  M.A.^This 
work  includes  Mythical  Names  ;  including  also  Pseudonyms,  Nick-names  of 
eminent  persons  and  parties,  &c.  <S:c. 

This  work  may  also  be  had  scpai'ately,  post  ^vo.  price  ^s. 

A  Pronouncing  Vocabulary  of  Scripture  Proper  Names.  By  W,  A. 
Wheeler.  M.A. 

A  Pronouncing  Vocabulary  of  Greek  and  Latin  Proper  Names.  By 
Prof.  Thacher. 

An  Etymological  Vocabulary  of  Modern  Geographical  Names.  By  the 
Rev.  C.  H.  Wheeler. 

Pronouncing  Vocabularies  of  Modern  Geographical  and  Biographical 
Names.     By  J.  Thomas,  M.D, 

A  Pronouncing  Vocabulary  of  Common  English  Christian  Names,  with 
their  derivations,  signification,  &c. 

A  Dictionary  of  Quotations.  Containing  all  Words,  Phrases,  Proverbs,  and 
Colloquial  Expressions  from  the  Greek,  Latin,  and  Modem  Languages  met 
with  in  literature. 

A  New  Biographical  Dictionary  of  upwards  of  9700  Names  of  Noted 
Persons,  Ancient  and  Modern. 

A  List  of  Abbreviations,  Contractions,  and  Arbitrary  Signs  used  in 
Writing  and  Printing. 

A  Classified  Selection  of  Pictorial  Illustrations  (70  pages).  With 
references  to  the  text. 

'  The  cheapest  Dictionary  ever  published,  as  it  is  confessedly  one  of  the  best.  The  Intro 
duction  of  small  woodcut  illustrations  of  technical  and  scientific  terms  adds  greatly  to  the 
utility  of  the  Dictionary.' — Churchman. 


\1.  lis,  6d.  ;  half-calf,  2/.  ;  calf  or  half-russia,  2/.  2s.  ;  russia,  2/.  los. 


LONDON : 

Printed  by  Strangewavs  and  Sons,  Tower  Street,  Upper  St.  Martin's  Lane. 


Sanies 


JIY 


^KY,tliis 
liiis  lave 


ler,M,A, 
I'liorities, 


Aim 
sanies  oi 


yW.A. 

m.  By 
.  By  the 
UPHICAL 
MES,witll 

lagesiael 
f  Noted 

ll'SEDK 

i).  w 

TkeinW- 
ally  10  tie