Skip to main content

Full text of "A history of European thought in the nineteenth century"

See other formats


/  UJU 


EUROPEAN  THOUGHT  IN  THE  NINETEENTH 
CENTURY 


Toiovros  ow  /u,oi  6  onryypa^evs  €ora>, 
£evos  ev  rot?  ^St^SXtois  xai 


—  LUCIAN. 


A   HISTORY 


OF 


EUBOPEAN     THOUGHT 


IN    THE 


NINETEENTH   CENTUEY 


BY 

JOHN    THEODOKE    MEEZ 


VOL.  I. 


THIRD   UNALTERED   EDITION 


WILLIAM    BLACKWOOD    AND    SONS 

EDINBURGH     AND     LONDON 
MCMVII 


All  Rights  reserved 


PREFACE. 


As  the  plan  of  this  work  is  fully  given  in  the  Introduction, 
only  a  few  points,  chietiy  of  a  personal  character,  remain  to 
be  touched  on  here. 

The  first  refers  to  the  motive  which  led  me  to  a  course 
of  studies,  extending  over  more  than  thirty  years,  of  which 
this  book  is  the  outcome. 

The  object  of  the  book  is  philosophical,  in  the  sense  now 
accepted  by  many  and  by  divergent  schools — i.e.,  it  desires 
to  contribute  something  towards  a  unification  of  thought. 
When  in  the  beginning  of  my  philosophical  studies  I  be- 
came convinced  that  this  is  the  task  of  philosophy,  I  felt 
the  necessity  of  making  myself  acquainted,  at  first  hand, 
with  the  many  trains  of  reasoning  by  which,  in  the 
separate  domains  of  science,  of  practical  and  of  individual 
thought,  such  a  unification  has  been  partially  and  success- 
fully attempted.  Such  a  survey  seemed  to  me  indispens- 
able. The  possession  of  a  map  showing  the  many  lines  of 
thought  which  our  age  has  cultivated  seemed  to  me  the 
first  requisite,  the  basis  from  which  a  more  complete 


VI  PREFACE. 

unification  would  have  to  start.  The  following  pages 
contain  the  result  of  this  survey.  Like  every  survey,  it 
can  claim  to  be  merely  an  approximation.  It  gives  outlines 
which  closer  scrutiny  will  have  to  correct  and  fill  up. 

My  original  intention  was  to  complete  this  survey  in 
three  volumes,  corresponding  to  the  three  divisions  of  the 
subject  set  out  in  the  Introduction. 

Some  of  my  friends,  who  desired  that  the  publication 
of  the  book  should  not  be  unduly  delayed,  considered  that 
the  Introduction  and  the  earlier  chapters  of  the  work  would 
give  something  intelligible  in  themselves,  and  urged  the 
advantage  of  smaller  volumes.  I  therefore  decided  to  com- 
plete the  first  part  of  the  history,  which  deals  with  scientific 
thought,  in  two  volumes  instead  of  in  one. 

For  the  information  of  my  readers,  I  mention  here  that 
the  two  last  chapters  of  this  volume,  which  treat  of  the 
astronomical  and  of  the  atomic  views  of  Nature,  will  be 
followed  in  the  second  volume  by  similar  chapters  on 
the  mechanical,  the  physical,  the  biological,  the  statistical, 
and  the  psychophysical  views  of  Nature,  and  that  it  is  my 
intention  to  close  the  first  part  of  my  subject  by  an  attempt 
to  trace  concisely  the  development  of  mathematical  thought 
in  this  century. 

My  thanks  are  due  to  many  friends  who  have  supported 
me  with  assistance  and  encouragement. 

I  consider  myself  fortunate  in  having  secured  for  the 
revision  of  the  whole  volume  the  invaluable  aid  of  Mr 
Thomas  Whittaker,  BJL,  whose  profound  erudition,  know- 


PREFACE.  Vll 

ledge  of  ancient  and  modern  literature,  and  great  editorial 
experience,  were  well  known  to  my  late  friend  Professor 
Groom  Eobertson,  during  his  successful  editorship  of  the 
first  series  of  'Mind.' 

Mr  S.  Oliver  Roberts,  M.A.,  of  the  Merchant  Taylors' 
School,  has  kindly  read  over  the  fourth,  aiid  Professor 
Phillips  Bedson,  of  the  Durham  College  of  Science  of  this 
city,  the  last,  chapter  of  this  volume.  The  Introduction  has 
greatly  benefited  by  a  thorough  revision  by  my  brother- 
in-law,  Dr  Spence  Watson,  a  master  of  the  English  language. 

I  must  also  thank  him  and  Dr  Thomas  Hodgkin  for 
having  given  me  what  I  value  as  much  as  assistance — 
namely,  encouragement. 

One  indeed  to  whom  I  am  in  this  respect  more  indebted, 
perhaps,  than  to  any  one  else — whom  to  have  known  has 
meant,  for  many,  a  revelation  of  the  power  of  mind  and 
the  reality  of  spirit — is  no  more :  Ernst  Curtius.  While 
I  was  writing  the  last  pages  of  this  volume,  in  which  he 
took  a  warm  interest,  the  tidings  arrived  that  he  had  passed 
away.  But  she  who  was  nearest  and  dearest  to  him  is 
still  with  us — a  true  priestess  of  the  higher  life,  who  has 
kept  burning  in  the  soul  of  many  a  youthful  friend  the 
spiritual  fire  when  it  was  in  danger  of  being  quenched  by 
the  growing  materialism  of  our  age. 

J.  THEO.  MERZ. 

THE  QUARRIES, 
NEWCASTLE-UPON-TYNE,  November  1896. 


CONTENTS  OF  THE  FIEST  VOLUME. 


INTRODUCTION. 

I.  Thought,  the  hidden  world,  1 ;  The  only  moving  principle,  2 ;  History  of 
Nature,  how  to  be  understood,  2  ;  Not  intelligible  without  intellect,  2 ; 
History  of  savage  tribes,  what  is  it  ?  3  ;  Two  ways  in  which  thought  enters 
into  history,  4  ;  Definition  of  thought  impossible,  4  ;  Relation  of  outer 
and  inner  worlds  undefined,  5  ;  Many  meanings  of  thought,  5  ;  Thought 
of  the  present  age,  6  ;  Contemporary  history,  to  what  extent  possible 
and  valuable,  6  ;  Supposed  objectivity  of  historians,  7  ;  Value  of  contem- 
porary records,  8  ;  Mystery  of  the  life  of  thought,  8  ;  Latent  thought  the 
material  for  genius,  8  ;  Contemporary  record  of  thought  more  faithful, 
10  ;  Events  of  the  immediate  past,  10  ;  Changes  of  language,  11 ;  Coining 
of  new  words,  12  ;  Object  of  this  work,  13  ;  Not  a  political  history,  nor  a 
history  of  science,  literature,  and  art,  13  ;  Influences  which  have  a  result 
on  our  inner  life,  14  ;  Personal  knowledge  necessary,  14  ;  American  influ- 
ence only  touched  upon,  14  ;  Only  French,  German,  and  English  thought 
treated,  15 ;  Unity  of  thought,  a  product  of  this  century,  16  ;  Voltaire, 
16;  Adam  Smith,  16;  Coleridge  and  Wordsworth,  17;  Mme.  de  Stael, 
17  ;  Paris  the  focus  of  science,  17  ;  Babbage,  Herschel,  and  Peacock,  18  ; 
Liebig's  laboratory,  18  ;  Comte's  philosophy,  18  ;  Constable's  influence  in 
France,  19  ;  Science  become  international,  19  ;  The  light  which  etymology 
throws  on  the  history  of  thought,  20  ;  Goethe,  22  ;  Peculiarity  of  the 
German  language,  22  ;  New  thought  has  found  new  words,  23  ;  De  Bon- 
aid  and  Max  Miiller,  23 ;  Thought,  how  expressed  in  French  and  Ger- 
man, 24  ;  Philosophy  of  history,  25 ;  Want  of  precise  terms  in  German 
and  French,  26  ;  Carlyle,  26. 


X  CONTEXTS. 

II.  The  two  factors  of  intellectual  progress,  27  ;    Object  of  the  book,  28  ; 

Nineteenth  century,  what  it  has  achieved  :  (a)  Method  of  knowledge  ;  (6) 
Unity  of  knowledge,  29  ;  Search  after  truth,  29  ;  Method  of  science,  prac- 
tised by  Galileo,  &c.,  defined  by  Bacon,  &c.,  30  ;  Disintegration  of  learn- 
ing, 30  ;  Apparent  distance  between  science  and  poetry,  31  ;  Closer  con- 
nection between  science  and  life,  31  ;  What  has  nineteenth  century  done 
for  the  ideals  ?  32 ;  Deeper  conception  of  the  unity  of  human  interests, 
33  ;  Different  terms  for  expressing  this  unity,  33  ;  Definition  of  thought, 
33  ;  Age  of  encyclopaedic  treatment  of  learning,  34  ;  Unity  of  knowledge 
gradually  lost  sight  of,  35  ;  Lectures  on  "  Encyclopadie  "  in  Germany,  37 ; 
Encyclopsedias  did  not  fulfil  their  promise,  39  ;  French  were  masters  in 
science  in  beginning  of  the  century,  41 ;  Reaction  in  Germany  against 
metaphysics,  43 ;  Reform  in  school  literature,  44  ;  Germany  has  taken 
the  lead  in  studying  the  life  of  thought,  46  ;  Transition  from  meta- 
physical to  historical  method,  47 ;  Herbert  Spencer,  48 ;  Lotze,  48 ; 
Herder's  'Ideen,'  50;  Humboldt's  'Kosmos,'  51  ;  Lotze's  '  Microcosmus,' 
52 ;  What  the  mental  life  of  mankind  consists  of,  55  ;  Methods  have 
their  day  and  cease  to  be,  56. 

III.  Necessity  of  choosing  a  road,  57  ;  No  central  event  in  our  age,  58  ;  Is 
history  of  thought  history  of  philosophy  ?    60 ;    Goethe's  work  involves 
the  deepest  thought  of  the  century,  61 ;  Philosophy  retrospective,  62  ; 
Two  questions,  63  ;  Speculation,  64  ;  Philosophy  defined,  65  ;   Division 
of  the  book,  65  ;  Neither  science  nor  philosophy  exhausts  "  thought,"  66  ; 
Thought  also  hidden  in  literature  and  art,  66  ;    Goethe's  and  Words- 
worth's influence,  67  ;  Unmethodical  thought,  68  ;  Summed  up  in  term 
"  religious  thought,"  69  ;  Science  is  exact,  69  ;  Subjective  interests,  70  ; 
Philosophy  intermediate  between  exact  science  and  religion,  71 ;  Three- 
fold aspect  of  thought :  scientific,  philosophical,  individual,  72  ;  Difficult 
to  separate  the  three  aspects,  74 ;   French  thought  centred  in  science, 
75  ;  State  of  philosophy  in  England,  75  ;  Goethe's  '  Faust '  representative 
of  the  thought  of  the  century,  76  ;  A  period  of  ferment,  76  :  Caused  by 
the  Revolution,  77  ;  Thought  of  century  partly  radical,  partly  reactionary, 
77  ;  Byronic  school,  78 ;  Revolutionary  theories,  79  ;  Thought  to  be  con- 
sidered as  a  constructive  power,  80 ;  Darwin,  Spencer,  and  Lotze,  81 ; 
Romanticism,  82 ;  Scientific  thought  to  be  dealt  with  first,  84  ;  Hegel's 
doctrine,  85. 


CONTENTS.  XI 


PAET   I.— SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

Three  chapters  on  the  growth  and  the  diffusion  of  the  scientific  spirit 
in  the  first  half  of  the  nineteenth  century. 


CHAPTER    I. 

THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN  FRANCE. 

Our  century  the  scientific  century,  89  ;  Difference  of  English  and  Continental 
notions  of  science,  91;  Relation  of,  science  and  life,  92;  Foreseen  by 
Bacon,  93  ;  Defect  in  Bacon's  Philosophy,  94  ;  Corrected  by  Newton,  95  ; 
Bacon's  and  Newton's  ideas  taken  up  by  French  philosophers  :  Bacon  and 
Newton  compared,  96  ;  Laplace's  work,  97  ;  French  Academy  of  Sciences, 
99 ;  Continental  methods  in  mathematics,  100 ;  Modern  analytical 
methods,  102 ;  Older  synthetical  methods,  103 ;  Influence  of  science 
on  French  literature,  104  ;  Absence  of  this  influence  in  England  and 
Germany,  106  ;  Schools  of  science  in  Paris,  106  ;  Promoted  by  Govern- 
ments of  Revolution,  108  ;  Condorcet,  110  ;  Lakanal,  111 ;  Ecole  normale, 
Ecole  polytechnique,  112  ;  Monge's  'Descriptive  Geometry,"  114  ;  Science 
of  Chemistry,  114  ;  New  mathematical  sciences,  116  ;  Crystallography, 
116  ;  Theory  of  probability,  118  ;  Laplace  gained  his  results  by  dis- 
regarding "individuality,"  124  ;  The  centre  of  interest  in  the  sciences  of 
life,  125 ;  Into  this  centre  Cuvier  carried  exact  research,  128 ;  Cuvier's 
training,  133  ;  Cuvier  the  greatest  representative  of  the  Academic  system, 
136 ;  Science  during  the  Revolution  and  First  Empire,  138  ;  Popular- 
isation of  science  in  France,  142 ;  Literary  and  national  popularisation, 
142 ;  Dangers  of  the  former,  143  ;  The  Revolution  added  the  practical 
popularisation,  145 ;  Influence  of  the  first  Napoleon  on  science,  149  ; 
Napoleon  favoured  the  mathematical  sciences,  151 ;  Discountenanced 
contemporary  philosophy,  152 ;  Used  statistical  methods,  153 ;  Promi- 
nence given  deservedly  to  French  names  by  Cuvier,  155. 

CHAPTER     II. 

THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 

Foundation  of  German  universities,  158  ;  Development  of  the  universities  by 
the  people,  159  ;  Geographical  distribution  of  the  universities,  162  ;  Full 
development  of  the  German  university  system,  163  ;  Philosophical  fac- 
ulty, 164;  University  of  Gottingen,  164;  Relation  of  universities  and 


Xll  CONTENTS. 

high  schools,  166 ;  The  university  a  training-school  for  research,  167  ; 
The  ideal  of  Wissenschaft,  168  ;  Developed  under  the  German  university 
system,  170  ;  Reception  of  exact  science  in  Germany,  174 ;  Science  not 
yet  domiciled  during  the  eighteenth  century,  178  ;  Scientific  periodicals, 
180;  Gauss's  mathematical  researches,  181;  Scientific  spirit  enters  the 
universities  in  second  quarter  of  century,  183  ;  Jacobi's  mathematical 
school,  185 ;  Chemical  laboratories  established  in  1826  through  Liebig, 
188 ;  Cosmopolitan  character  of  German  science,  189  ;  Liebig's  organic 
analysis,  191 ;  Biology  a  German  science,  193  ;  Cellular  theory  of 
Schleiden,  194  ;  and  Schwann,  195 ;  Ernst  Heinrich  Weber,  196 ;  and 
Johannes  Muller,  197  ;  Psychophysics,  198  ;  Spirit  of  exact  research  and 
Wissenschaft,  202 ;  Encyclopaedic  view  necessary  in  philosophy  and 
history,  203  ;  Philosophy  of  Nature,  204 ;  Conflict  between  the  scientific 
and  the  philosophical  views,  205  ;  A.  von  Humboldt,  206 ;  Influence  of 
Berzelius  on  German  science,  208 ;  Philosophy  of  Nature  and  medical 
science,  209  ;  Science  for  its  own  sake,  211  ;  Bequest  of  the  classical  and 
philosophical  school,  211 ;  Completeness  and  thoroughness  of  research, 
213  ;  Combination  of  research  and  teaching,  214  ;  Combination  of  science 
and  philosophy,  215 ;  Biology  grown  out  of  science  and  philosophy  com- 
bined, 216  ;  Du  Bois-Reymond  on  Muller,  217  ;  "Vital  force"  abandoned, 
218  ;  Mechanical  view  in  biology,  219  ;  Criticism  of  principles  of  mathe- 
matics, 221  ;  The  exact,  the  historical,  and  the  critical  habits  of  thought, 
222. 

CHAPTER    III. 

THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 

Scientific  organisation  abroad,  226  ;  Similar  institutions  in  Great  Britain,  227  ; 
English  science  in  the  early  part  of  the  century,  229  ;  Alleged  decline  of 
science  in  England,  230  ;  Criticisms  of  Playfair,  231  ;  Babbage's  criti- 
cisms, 233  ;  Foreign  opinions  on  English  science,  235  ;  English  replies  to 
Babbage,  238  ;  Foundation  of  the  British  Association,  238 ;  Character- 
istics of  higher  mental  work  in  England,  239  ;  Academies  and  universities 
not  always  impartial,  240 ;  Fourier,  241  ;  Fresnel,  241  ;  Plucker, 
242  ;  Grassmann,  243  ;  Central  organisation  wanting  in  England,  243  ; 
Thomas  Young,  244  ;  Dalton,  245  ;  Faraday,  246 ;  Green,  246  ;  Boole, 
247  ;  Babbage,  248  ;  Characteristics  of  English  thought,  249  ;  Absence  of 
schools  of  scientific  thought,  250  ;  Individual  character  and  practical 
tendency  of  English  science,  251  ;  English  peculiarities  more  pronounced 
during  earlier  part  of  the  century,  252 ;  Unique  character  of  English 
universities,  254  ;  Ideal  of  "liberal  education,"  255  ;  Union  of  education 
and  instruction,  258  ;  Educational  organisations  in  England,  262 ;  The 


CONTENTS.  Xlll 

Royal  Institution,  264 ;  Manchester  Literary  and  Philosophical  Society, 
265  ;  John  Dawson  of  Sedbergh,  267  ;  The  Scotch  Universities,  267  ;  The 
Royal  Society  of  Edinburgh,  269;  The  'Edinburgh  Review,'  270;  The 
Analytical  Society  of  Cambridge,  271  ;  University  life  in  Scotland,  271 ; 
The  Dublin  Mathematical  School,  274  ;  Importance  of  British  contribu- 
tions to  science,  276  ;  Diffusion  of  scientific  knowledge  on  the  Continent, 
276  ;  Isolation  of  English  men  of  science,  277 ;  Individualism  of  the 
English  character,  279  ;  Changes  during  the  last  fifty  years,  280  ;  British 
contributions  to  biology,  282  ;  Jenner,  284  ;  English  love  of  nature,  284  ; 
Union  of  individualism  and  naturalism  in  England,  286  ;  White  of  Sel- 
borne,  288  ;  The  Geological  Society,  290 ;  William  Smith,  291 ;  Charles 
Bell,  292  ;  Historical  Geography,  294  ;  Martin  William  Leake,  296  ;  Work 
of  the  three  nations  compared,  298. 

CHAPTER    IV. 

THE   ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW   OF   NATURE. 

The  scientific  spirit  in  the  first  and  second  half  of  the  century,  302  ;  Science 
become  international,  303  ;  Disappearance  of  national  differences,  305 ; 
Special  scientific  ideas,  306 ;  Philosophy  of  science,  306 ;  Whewell's 
'History'  and  'Philosophy,'  309  ;  Philosophy  and  science,  311  ;  Leading 
scientific  ideas  mostly  very  ancient,  312 ;  Mathematical  spirit,  314  ; 
When  first  introduced  into  science,  317  ;  Newton's  '  Principia,'  318  ;  The 
gravitation  formula,  319;  Lines  of  thought  emanating  from  it,  321  ; 
Element  of  error,  323  ;  Laplace  and  Newton,  326  ;  Several  interests 
which  promote  science,  326 ;  Insufficiency  of  observation,  328  ;  Practical 
interest,  328  ;  Focalising  effect  of  mathematical  formula),  332 ;  Matter 
and  force  mathematically  defined,  334 ;  Weight  and  mass,  336  ;  Gravi- 
tation not  an  ultimate  property  of  matter,  338  ;  Attraction  and  repulsion, 
342  ;  Electrical  and  magnetic  action,  344  ;  Law  of  emanations,  344  ; 
Molecular  action,  346  ;  The  astronomical  view  :  Cosmical,  molar,  and 
molecular  phenomena,  348 ;  Special  interest  attached  to  molar  dimen- 
sions, 350  ;  Geometrical  axioms,  352  ;  Difficulty  of  measuring  gravitation 
directly,  353  ;  Astronomical  view  of  molecular  phenomena,  354 ;  Capil- 
lary attraction,  356 ;  Boscovich's  extension  of  the  Newtonian  formula, 
357  ;  Coulomb's  measurements,  360 ;  Extended  by  Gauss  and  Weber, 
360  ;  Davy  and  Faraday,  363  ;  Ampere  and  Weber  develop  the  astro- 
nomical view,  366 ;  Weber's  fundamental  measurements,  368  ;  Necessity 
of  developing  the  infinitesimal  methods,  373  ;  Newtonian  formula  the 
basis  of  physical  astronomy,  375  ;  The  Newtonian  formula  unique  as  to 
universality  and  accuracy,  377 ;  Is  it  an  ultimate  law  ?  378  ;  Laplace's 
opinion,  378  ;  Opposition  to  the  astronomical  view  of  nature,  381. 


XIV  CONTENTS. 

CHAPTER   V. 

THE   ATOMIC   VIEW    OF   XATURE. 

Recapitulation,  382 ;  Atomic  theory,  235  ;  Lavoisier,  386  ;  Phlogistic  theory, 
388  ;  Theory  of  combustion,  389  ;  Rule  of  fixed  proportions,  392  ;  J. 
Benjamin  Richter,  393  ;  Dalton,  394 ;  Berzelius,  396  ;  Atomic  theory 
and  gravitation  compared,  396  ;  Wollaston's  prophecy,  397  ;  Rule  of 
multiple  proportions,  398;  Equivalents,  399;  "Simplex  sigillum  veri," 
401  ;  Prout's  hypothesis,  402  ;  Discovery  of  Isomerism,  405  ;  Organic 
Chemistry,  407;  Liebig's  definition  of  same,  409;  Type  theory,  411; 
Uncertainty  in  chemical  theory  about  middle  of  century,  413  ;  Two 
aspects  of  the  atomic  theory,  415  ;  A  convenient  symbolism,  417  ; 
Neglect  of  the  study  of  affinity,  420;  Kopp  on  chemical  theory  in  1873, 
421  ;  The  periodic  law,  422  ;  Difference  between  chemical  and  physical 
reasoning,  424  ;  The  kinetic  theory  of  gases,  425  ;  Avogadro's  hypothesis, 
427 ;  Neglect  of  same,  429 ;  Development  of  the  atomic  view,  431  ; 
Pasteur's  discovery  of  "Chirality,"  431;  Atom  and  molecule,  432; 
Joule's  calculations,  434 ;  Clausius's  first  memoir,  435  ;  Internal  energy 
of  molecules,  436 ;  The  atomic  theory  accepted  as  a  physical  theory 
about  1860,  437  ;  Clerk  Maxwell :  The  statistical  view  of  nature,  438  ; 
Doctrine  of  averages,  440  ;  Geometrical  arrangement  of  atoms,  441  ; 
Crystallography,  441  ;  Analogy  between  crystallographic  and  atomic 
laws,  444 ;  Isomorphism,  444 ;  Polymorphism,  446 ;  Structural  and 
stereo-chemistry,  447  ;  Valency,  447  ;  Atomic  linkage,  449  ;  The  carbon 
tetrahedron,  450 ;  Defects  and  insufficiency  of  the  atomic  view,  451  ; 
Theories  of  chemical  affinity,  452  ;  Practical  influences,  453  ;  Change  in 
definition  of  organic  chemistry,  454  ;  Criticisms  of  the  atomic  view,  455. 


A  HISTOKY  OF  EUROPEAN  THOUGHT 
IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY, 


INTEODUCTIOK 
I. 

BEHIND  the  panorama  of   external  events   and   changes        i- 

Thought, 

which  history  unfolds  before  our  view  there  lies  the  *0er{1didden 
hidden  world  of  desires  and  motives,  of  passions  and 
energies,  which  produced  or  accompanied  them ;  behind 
the  busy  scenes  of  Life  lie  the  inner  regions  of  Thought. 
Only  when  facts  and  events  cease  to  be  unconnected, 
when  they  appear  to  us  linked  together  according  to 
some  design  and  purpose,  leading  us  back  to  some 
originating  cause  or  forward  to  some  denned  end,  can 
we  speak  of  History  in  the  sense  which  the  word  has 
acquired  in  modern  language ;  and  similarly  do  the 
hidden  motives,  desires,  and  energies  which  underlie  or 
accompany  the  external  events  require  to  be  somehow 
connected,  to  present  themselves  in  some  order  and  con- 
tinuity, before  we  are  able  to  grasp  and  record  them. 
VOL.  i.  A 


2  INTRODUCTION. 

That  which  has  made  facts  and  events  capable  of  being 
chronicled  and  reviewed,  that  which  underlies  and  con- 
nects them,  that  which  must  be  reproduced  by  the  his- 
torian who  unfolds  them  to  us,  is  the  hidden  element  of 

2.  Thought.     Thought,  and  thought  alone,  be  it  as  a  principle 
the  only'      of   action  or  as  the   medium  of  after-contemplation,  is 

moving 

principle,  capable  of  arranging  and  connecting,  of  combining  what 
is  isolated,  of  moving  that  which  is  stagnant,  of  propel- 
ling that  which  is  stationary.  Take  away  thought,  and 
monotony  becomes  the  order. 

3.  This  assertion  may  seem  bold  to  many,  who  would  look 

History  of 

Nature,  how  rather  to  the  grand  phenomena  of  Nature  than  to  the 

to  be  under- 
narrOW  limits  of  man's  activity.     A  few  remarks  will, 

however,  suffice  to  show  that  my  proposition  is  not 
opposed  to  the  view  which  they  take.  ,  It  may  be 
urged  that,  independent  of  human  life  altogether,  the 
earth  has  a  history,  the  planetary  system  has  a  develop- 
ment, and  that,  according  to  modern  theories,  evolution 
is  the  principle  which  governs  inanimate  as  well  as  ani- 
mated nature ;  that  rest  and  sameness  are  nowhere  to 

4.  be  found,  everywhere  change  and  unrest.     But  change 

Not  intelli- 

gibie  with-    and  unrest  do  not  necessarily  constitute  history.    Motion 

out  mtel-  »  » 

and  change  would  be  as  monotonous  as  absolute  rest, 
were  they  merely  to  repeat  themselves  endlessly,  did  the 
whole  movement  not  produce  something  more,  and  were 
this  something  more  not  greater  or  better  than  the 
beginning.  But  greater  and  better  are  terms  which  imply 
comparison  by  a  thinking  beholder,  who  attaches  to  one 
thing  a  greater  value  than  to  another,  judging  by  certain 
ideal  standards,  which  are  not  in  the  objects  or  process  of 
nature  themselves,  but  are  contained  only  in  his  own  think- 


INTRODUCTION.  3 

ing  mind.  It  may  be  that  a  mechanical  and  mindless  series 
of  changes  can  produce  numbers  without  end,  or  forms  of 
countless  variety:  but  this  process  would  deserve  the  name 
of  history  only  if  either  the  transition  from  unity  to  mul- 
tiplicity, or  the  production  of  formal  variety,  were  capable 
of  being  understood  by  a  thinking  mind, — if  the  result 
of  the  process  were  a  matter  of  some  concern,  if  an 
interest  were  attached  to  it,  if  a  gain  or  loss  could  be 
recorded.  The  pendulum  which  swings  backwards  and 
forwards  in  endless  monotony,  the  planet  which  moves 
round  the  sun  in  unceasing  repetition,  the  atom  of  matter 
which  vibrates  in  the  same  path,  have  for  us  no  interest 
beyond  the  mathematical  formulae  which  govern  their 
motions,  and  which  permit  us  mentally  to  reproduce,  i.e., 
to  think  them.  A  combination  of  an  infinite  number  of 
these  elementary  movements  would  have  as  little  interest, 
were  it  not  that  out  of  such  a  combination  there  resulted 
something  novel  and  unforeseen :  something  that  was 
beautiful  to  behold  or  useful  to  possess,  something  that 
was  valuable  to  a  thinking  mind  in  a  higher  or  lower 
meaning  of  the  word. 

But  if,  even  in  inanimate  nature,  the  processes  of  change 
acquire  an  interest,  possess  a  history,  only  if  referred  to 
a  thinking  mind  which  can  record,  understand,  and  appre- 
ciate them,  how  much  more  is  this  the  case  when  we  deal 
with  human  affairs,  where  man  is  not  only  the  thinking 
beholder  but  the  principal  agent  ?  Here  the  historic 
interest  would  cease,  were  the  succeeding  years  and  ages 
to  produce  no  valuable  change,  were  the  rule  of  existence 
and  the  order  of  life  to  repeat  themselves  in  unceasing 
monotony.  The  savage  tribes  of  Africa  have  a  history:  but  is  it? ' 


INTRODUCTION. 


ft, 

Two  way* 
in  which 
Ti.ou.-h: 
enters  into 
History. 


Definition 
of  Thonght 
impossible. 


this  history  is  all  known  when  the  order  of  the  day,  the 
year,  at  most  of  a  generation,  is  known.  Even  the  highly 
complicated  but  stagnant  life  of  China  would  have  a  short 
historical  record — many  thousands  of  years  taking  up  no 
more  space  than  as  many  days  of  modem  European  history: 

"Better  fifty  years  of  Europe  than  a  cycle  of  Cathay." 

Thus  it  is  that  Thought  becomes  in  two  ways  a  subject 
of  great  interest  and  importance  to  the  historian.  Of 
every  change  in  nature  or  human  life  we  can  ask :  What 
has  been  its  result  in  the  world  of  thought  ?  What 
gain  or  loss,  what  progress,  has  it  worked  in  the  minds 
of  men,  of  us  the  beholders  ?  Has  it  increased  our 
knowledge,  enriched  our  stock  of  ideas,  deepened  our 
insight,  broadened  our  views  and  sympathies — in  one 
word,  has  it  added  to  our  interests  ?  has  it  made  larger 
and  fuller  our  inner  life  ? 

And  of  every  change  in  human  affairs  we  can  ask  this 
further  question :  What  part  has  thought,  the  inner  life, 
played  in  this  change  ?  These  two  questions  mark  the 
task  of  the  historian  of  Thought. 

I  do  not  think  it  necessary  or  practicable  at  this  stage 
to  explain  minutely  the  terms  with  which  we  have  so 
far  been  dealing.  Many  a  one  might  be  tempted  to  ask 
for  a  definition  of  Thought,  or  for  a  preciser  statement  of 
the  actual  relation  between  Xature,  Life,  and  Thought.1 


1  In  refusing  to  define  what  I 
mean  by  Thought.  I  take  up  the 
opposite  position  to  that  occupied 
by  Prof.  Max  Muller  in  his  latest 
work,  "The  Science  of  Thought,' 
London,  188",  p.  1.  where  he  says  : 
"  I  mean  by  Thought  the  act  of 
thinking,  and  by  thinking  I  mean 


no  more  than  combining.  I  do 
not  pretend  that  others  have  not 
the  right  of  using  Thought  in  any 
sense  which  they  prefer,  provided 
only  that  they  will  clearly  define 
it."  So  far  as  definition  is  at  all  a 
part  of  the  work  of  the  historian. 
I  maintain  that  it  is  the  result  and 


INTRODUCTION. 


Such  definitions  must  be  left  to  the  reader  himself,  if 
in  course  of  the  perusal  of  these  volumes  he  finds  it 
necessary  to  form  abstract  theories  on  these  points. 
Any  definition  given  now  would  inevitably  involve  us  in 
controversies,  which  would  be  embarrassing  and  con- 
fusing. I  rely  upon  the  general  and  undefined  sense  of 
the  word  Thought,  assuming  that  every  one  will  connect 
some  intelligible  meaning  with  it,  some  meaning  which 
will  enable  him  to  understand  the  very  general  pro- 
position with  which  we  started,  the  existence  of  an  s. 

Relation  of 

inner   or    hidden  world  behind   the   world   of    external  outer  and 

inner  world 

events  and  facts,  the  continually  changing  nature  of  undefined, 
this  inner  world,  and  the  connection  and  reaction  be- 
tween the  two  worlds.  Whether  in  time  and  in  im- 
portance the  outer  or  the  inner  world  is  the  first, 
whether  within  the  latter  equal  value  attaches  to  the 
clearer  province  of  Reason,  i.e.,  defined  Thought,  to  the 
obscurer  regions  of  Feeling  and  Imagination,  and  to  the 
unconscious  world  of  Impulse,  these  are  questions  which 
it  is  not  necessary  to  answer  at  present.  As  it  was 
enough  to  point  to  the  existence  of  the  two  worlds  of 
Life  and  Thought,  so  it  will  be  enough  to  notice  that 
thought  does  not  mean  merely  defined,  clear,  methodical  9. 

Many  mean- 

thought,  but  likewise  the  great  region  of  desire,  impulse,  l^n°J 
feeling,   and  imagination,  all   of   which  play,  we   must 
admit,  a  great  part  in  the  inner  life  of  the  soul  as  well 
as  in  that  of  the  outer  world. 


Thought. 


outcome  of  his  narrative,  the  im- 
pression which  he  leaves  on  the 
mind  of  the  reader  when  he  has 
perused  the  work.  History  is  not 
mainly  a  science  which  proceeds 
by  analysis ;  it  is  the  attempt  to 


collect  and  arrange  in  a  living  pic- 
ture an  enormous  mass  of  detail. 
Too  rigid  definitions,  like  lines 
which  are  too  hard  and  marked, 
spoil  the  total  effect. 


6  INTRODUCTION. 

In  this  sense  of  the  word  we  have  in  the  following 
treatise  to  deal  with  the  History  of  Thought :  not,  how- 
ever, with  the  history  of  thought  in  general,  but  with 

10.  that  of  a  defined  period,  with  that  of  the  present  age 

Thought  of  ii'  •       r 

tue  present  and  the  age  immediately  preceding  it, — the  age,  in  tact, 
to  which  the  writer  and  his  readers  belong,  of  which 
they  have  a  personal  knowledge  and  recollection  more  or 
less  wide  and  intimate.  It  is  the  latter  circumstance 
which  has  made  me  select  this  special  portion  of  the 
history  of  thought;  for  it  is  that  portion  of  which,  it 
seems  to  me,  I  and  my  contemporaries  should — if  we  go 
about  it  in  the  right  way — know  most.  As  every  person 
is  his  own  best  biographer,  so  it  seems  to  me  every  age 
is,  in  a  certain  sense,  its  own  best  historian. 

11.  We  know  that  this  has  been  frequently  denied  so  far 

Contempor- 
ary history,  as  external  events  (that  which  many  persons  call  history 

andtvjauible  ?>ar  ejl-Ce^ence)  are  concerned.  Contemporary  writers  do 
not,  it  is  stated,  get  beyond  mere  records  of  events, 
records  at  once  one-sided,  incomplete,  and  confusing.  It 
is  indeed  necessary  to  have  the  records  in  great  number 
and  variety :  because  the  true  and  real  record  can  only 
be  given  by  him  who  combines  all  these  many  records 
into  one,  who  avoids  the  errors  arising  from  special 
points  of  view,  from  narrowness  of  outlook,  from  indi- 
vidual ignorance,  blindness,  or  prejudice.  Still,  in  spite 
of  such  defects,  the  contemporary  records  will  always 
remain  the  most  valuable  sources  for  the  future  historian 
who  may  succeed  in  sifting  their  various  testimonies, 
combining  and  utilising  them  to  produce  a  fuller  and 
more  consistent  picture  of  the  bygone  age.  But  while 
his  work  may  be  only  temporarily  valuable,  theirs  is 


INTRODUCTION. 


lasting.  It  is  hardly  doubtful  that,  after  hundreds  or 
thousands  of  years  have  passed,  the  simple,  detailed,  and 
perhaps  contradictory,  narratives  of  contemporary  wit- 
nesses will  outlive  those  more  elaborate  and  artistic 
efforts  of  the  historian  which  are  so  largely  inspired  and 
coloured  by  the  convictions  of  another — viz.,  his  own — 
age.  For  as  Goethe  has  remarked  :  "  History  must  from 
time  to  time  be  rewritten,  not  because  many  new  facts 
have  been  discovered,  but  because  new  aspects  come  into 
view,  because  the  participant  in  the  progress  of  an  age 
is  led  to  standpoints  from  which  the  past  can  be  re- 
garded and  judged  in  a  novel  manner."1 

Most  of  the  great  historians  whom  our  age  has  pro- 
duced will,  centuries  hence,  probably  be  more  interesting 
as  exhibiting  special  methods  of  research,  special  views 
on  political,  social,  and  literary  progress,  than  as  faith- 
ful and  reliable  chroniclers  of  events ;  and  the  objectivity  12. 
on  which  some  of  them  pride  themselves  will  be  looked  objectivity 

of  histor- 

upon  not  as  freedom  from  but  as  unconsciousness  on  their  ians- 
part  of  the  preconceived  notions  which  have  governed 
them.  But  where  the  facts  recorded  and  the  mind  which 
records  them  both  belong  to  the  same  age,  we  have  a 
double  testimony  regarding  that  age.  The  events,  and 
the  contemplating  mind,  supplement  each  other  to  form 
a  more  complete  picture,  inasmuch  as  the  matter  and  the 
medium  through  which  it  is  viewed  belong  to  the  same 
time.  And  so  it  comes  to  pass  that  historians  like 
Thucydides,  Tacitus,  and  Machiavelli  are  looked  upon  as 


1  '  Materialien  zur  Geschichte  der 
Farbenlehre,'  Werke,  2te  Abtheil- 
ung,  Band  3,  p.  239.  I  quote  from 


the  new  edition,  brought   out  by 
the  German  Goethe  Society. 


8  INTRODUCTION. 

perfect  models  in  the  art  of  writing   history,  and   the 
memoirs  of  many  modern  statesmen  are  more  lastingly 
valuable  than  the  more  elaborate  and  connected  narra- 
tives of  remote  and  secluded  scholars. 
is.  But  if  the  contemporary  record  of  facts  will  alwavs 

Value  of 

contempor-   have  a  peculiar  value,  however  incomplete  it  may  be, 


RurtsMid  stiH  more  must  this  be  the  case  with  the  contemporary 
Thonsht  record  of  thought  ;  especially  if  thought  means  the  whole 
of  the  inner  life  of  an  age,  not  merely  that  portion  which 
in  the  form  of  defined  thought  has  been  incorporated  in 
the  written  literature  of  the  age.  For  a  large  portion  of 
this  hidden  life  is  known  only  to  those  who  have  taken 

14.  part  in  it.     The  vague  yearnings  of  thousands  who  never 
the  Life  of    succeed  either  in  satisfying  or  expressing  them,  the  hun- 

dreds of  failures  which  never  become  known,  the  number- 
less desires  which  live  only  in  the  hearts  of  men  or  are 
painted  only  in  their  living  features,  the  uncounted 
strivings  after  solutions  of  practical  problems  dictated 
by  ambition  or  by  want,  the  many  hours  spent  by 
labourers  of  science  in  unsuccessful  attempts  to  solve 
the  riddles  of  nature,  —  all  these  hidden  and  forgotten 
efforts  form  indeed  the  bulk  of  a  nation's  thought,  of 
which  only  a  small  fraction  comes  to  the  surface,  or  shows 
itself  in  the  literature,  science,  poetry,  art,  and  prac- 

15.  tical  achievements  of  the  age.     Equally  important,  though 
Thoogbt      not   equally    prominent,    this    large    body  of    forgotten 
for  genius,    thought   has    nevertheless    been   that   which   made   the 

measure  full,  which  heaped  the  fuel  ready  for  the 
match  to  kindle  ;  it  constitutes  the  great  propelling  force 
which,  stored  up,  awaits  the  time  and  aid  of  individual 
talent  or  genius  to  set  it  free.  Philosophers  tell  us  of 


INTRODUCTION. 


the  wastefulness  of  organic  life,  of  the  thousands  of  germs 
which  perish,  of  the  huge  volume  of  seed  scattered  use- 
lessly. A  similar  fate  seems  to  fall  on  the  larger  portion 
of  intellectual  and  moral  effort ;  but  here  a  deeper  con- 
viction tells  us  that  it  is  not  the  sacrifice  but  the  co- 
operation of  the  many  which  makes  the  few  succeed, 
that  excellence  is  the  prize  of  united  effort,  that  many 
must  run  so  that  one  may  reach  a  higher  goal.  What 
other  feeling  could  console  those  legions  of  honest  workers 
who  spend  their  lives  in  trying  to  deal  with  the  seem- 
ingly unconquerable  host  of  social  evils,  the  apparently 
growing  vice  and  misery  of  large  towns,  who  raise  a 
cry  for  oppressed  nationalities,  or  preach  against  the 
curses  of  war  and  militarism  ?  Or  what  higher  and  un- 
selfish satisfaction  could  an  author  derive  from  spending 
half  a  lifetime  in  producing  a  work  which  in  the  end 
may  fall  dead-born  from  the  press,  if  it  were  not  the 
conviction  that  in  the  cause  in  which  he  has  failed 
another  after  him  may  succeed,  and  that  his  failure 
may  be  a  portion  of  the  silent  and  hidden  efforts  that 
co-operate  towards  a  useful  end  ? l  But  who  in  after- 
ages  can  write  the  history  of  this  forgotten  and  hidden 
work  of  a  nation  ?  Whose  historical  sense  is  delicate 
enough  to  feel  where  the  pressure  was  greatest  and  the 
effort  longest  ere  the  new  life  appeared,  whose  eye  pene- 
trating and  discerning  enough  to  follow  up  the  dim  streaks 


1  "Sehen  wir  nun  wiihrend  un- 
seres  Lebensganges  dasjenige  von 
auderen  gelestet,  wozu  wir  selbst 
f riiher  einen  Beruf  f iihlteu,  ihn  aber, 
mit  manchem  andern,  aufgeben 
mussten,  dann  tritt  das  schb'ne 
Gefiihl  ein,  dass  die  Menschheit  zu- 


sammen  erst  der  wahre  Mensch  ist, 
und  dass  der  Einzelne  nur  froh 
und  gliicklich  sein  kann,  wenn  er 
den  Muth  hat,  sich  ira  Ganzen  zu 
fiihlen."— Goethe,  'Wahrheit  und 
Dichtung,'  9th  Book;  Werke,  27, 
277. 


10 


INTRODUCTION. 


16. 

Contempor- 
ary record 
of  Thought 
more  faith- 
ful. 


17. 

Events  of 
the  imme- 
diate past. 


of  twilight,  dazzled  as  he  must  be  by  the  blaze  of  the 
risen  sun  ?  "VVe  who  live  in  the  expectation  of  the  light 
which  is  to  come,  surrounded  by  the  shadows,  difficulties, 
and  obstacles ;  we  who  belong  to  the  army,  and  are  not 
leaders,  who  live  in,  not  after,  the  fight, — we  claim  to  be 
better  able  to  tell  the  tale  of  endless  hopes  and  endeav- 
ours, of  efforts  common  to  many,  of  the  hidden  intellec- 
tual and  moral  work  of  our  age.1 

How  far  back  we  who  have  lived  during  the  second 
half  of  the  present  century  may  extend  the  period  of 
which  we  claim  to  have  a  personal  knowledge,  is  a  point 
of  further  interest.  Certain  it  is  that  in  our  parents  and 
immediate  forefathers  we  have  known  the  representatives 
of  a  generation  which  witnessed  and  laboured  in  the  in- 
terests of  the  great  Anti-Slavery,  the  Keform,  and  the  Anti- 
Corn-Law  movements,  who  experienced  the  revolutions 
worked  by  the  introduction  of  steam-power  and  gas,  who 
took  part  in  the  great  work  of  national  and  popular  edu- 
cation abroad  and  in  the  reform  of  school-life  in  England. 
They  themselves  went  through  the  enthusiasm  of  the 
anti-Xapoleonic  Eevolution  in  Germany,  came  under  the 
influence  of  Goethe's  mature  manhood,  were  fascinated  by 
the  stories  from  the  pen  of  the  Wizard  of  the  Xorth,  par- 


1  Compare  what  A.  de  Tocqueville 
says, '  (Euv.  comp.,'  vol.  viii.  p.  170  : 
"  Nous  sommes  encore  trop  pres  des 
evenements  pour  en  counaitre  les 
details.  Cela  parait  singulier,  mais 
est  vrai.  Les  details  ne  s'appren- 
nent  que  par  les  revelations  post- 
humes,  contenues  dans  les  Me- 
moires,  et  sont  souvent  ignores  des 
contemporains.  Ce  qu'ils  savent 
mieux  que  la  posterite,  c'est  le 


mouvement  des  esprits,  les  pas- 
sions generates  du  temps,  dont  ila 
sentent  encore  les  derniers  fremis- 
sements  dans  leur  esprit  ou  dans 
leur  cojur  ;  c'est  le  rapport  vrai  des 
principaux  personuages  et  des  prin- 
cipaux  faits  entre  eux.  Voila  ce 
que  les  voisins  des  temps  racoute"s 
apergoivent  mieux  que  ne  fait  la 
posterite." 


INTRODUCTION.  11 

took  of  the  spirit  of  the  Eomantic  School,  felt  the  electrical 
touch  of  Lord  Byron's  verse,  listened  to  the  great  orators 
of  the  third  French  Eevolution,  and  could  tell  us  of  the 
now  forgotten  spell  which  Napoleon  I.  exercised  over 
millions  of  reluctant  admirers.  Most  of  these  fascinations 
and  interests  live  only  in  the  narratives  of  contemporaries 
and  surviving  witnesses,  few  of  whom  have  succeeded  in 
perpetuating  them  with  pen  or  brush,  making  them  intel- 
ligible to  a  future  age ;  most  of  them  die  with  the  genera- 
tion itself.  Not  only  have  we  listened  to  their  words  and 
seen  in  their  features  the  traces  of  the  anxieties  they  lived 
through,  in  their  eyes  the  reflected  enthusiasms  and  as- 
pirations, in  their  glances  and  in  the  trembling  of  their 
voices  the  last  quiverings  of  bygone  passion  and  joy, — we 
have  received  from  them  a  still  more  eloquent  testimonial, 
a  more  living  inheritance.  But  this  we  cannot  hand 
down  to  our  children  in  the  form  in  which  it  was  given 
to  us :  it  has  not  passed  through  our  hands  unaltered. 
This  inheritance  is  the  language  which  our  parents  have 
taught  us.  Unknowingly  they  have  themselves  altered  is. 

Changes 

the  tongue,  the  words  and  sentences,  which  they  received,  which  Lan- 
guage under- 
depositing  in  these  altered  words  and  modes  of  speech  the  ^renuS1 

spirit,  the  ideas,  the  thought  of  their  lifetime.     These  p^f  of  the 
words  and  modes  of  speech  they  handed   to  us  in  our  Hfeof1"8 
infancy,  as  the  mould  wherein  to  shape  our  minds,  as  the 
shell  wherein  to  envelop  our  slowly  growing  thoughts,  as 
the  instrument  with  which  to  convey  our  ideas.     In  their 
language,  in  the  phrases  and  catchwords  peculiar  to  them, 
we  learnt  to  distinguish  what  was  important  and  interest- 
ing from  what  was  trivial  or  indifferent,  the  subjects  which 


12  INTRODUCTION. 

should  occupy  our  thoughts,  the  aims  we  should  follow, 
the  principles  and  methods  which  we  should  make  use  of. 
The  bulk  and  substance  of  this  they  indeed  inherited  them- 
selves; but  the  finer  distinctions  of  their  reasoning,  the 
delicate  shading  of  their  feelings  and  aspirations,  they 
added  and  modified  for  themselves,  modelling  for  their  own 
special  use  the  pliable  and  elastic  medium  of  the  mother 
tongue.  With  this  finer  moulding  we  have  inherited  the 
spirit  of  the  former  generation  :  predisposing  us  to  certain 
phases  of  thought  and  placing  in  our  path  a  difficulty  in 
acquiring  otherwise  than  by  gradual  and  almost  imper- 
ceptible degrees  the  faculty  of  assimilating  new  and  un- 
expected opinions,  tastes,  and  feelings.  Many  of  us  adhere 
to  the  special  character  and  phase  of  thought  acquired 
in  our  youth.  Some  by  learning  foreign  languages,  and 
living  in  other  countries,  gain  a  facility  for  understanding 
quite  different  phases  of  thought :  very  few  among  us 
19.  develop  so  much  original  thought  that  they  burst  the 

Inadequacy      in*  •         i  i  •     • 

ofconven-    shell  of  conventional  speech,  coining  new  words  and  ex- 

tional 

o?feinaifor  Pressi°ns  f°r  themselves,  embodying  in  them  the  fleeting 
c^to£"of  ideas  of  their  time,  the  indefinable  spirit  of  their  age. 
Once  expressed,  these  new  terms  are  rapidly  circulated, 
and  if  we  look  back  on  the  period  of  a  generation,  we 
note  easily  the  progress  and  development  of  opinion  and 
tastes  in  the  altered  terms  and  style  of  our  language. 

Thus  it  is  that  the  writer,  and  those  of  his  readers 
whose  memory  carries  them  back  to  the  middle  of  the 
century,  and  whose  schooling  and  education  embodied  the 
ideas  of  a  generation  before  that  time,  can  claim  to  have 
some  personal  knowledge  of  the  greater  portion  of  the 
nineteenth  century,  of  the  interests  which  it  created  and 


INTRODUCTION. 


13 


the  thoughts  which  stirred  it.1     It  is  the  object  of  these       20. 

Object  of 

volumes  to  fix,  if  possible,  this  possession ;  to  rescue  from  J^™* 
oblivion  that  which  appears  to  me  to  be  our  secret  prop-  Thought* 
erty ;  in  the  last  and  dying  hour  of  a  remarkable  age  to  dyhiggcen-ie 
throw  the  light  upon  the  fading  outlines  of  its  mental 
life  ;  to  try  to  trace  them,  and  with  the  aid  of  all  possible 
information,  gained  from  the  written  testimonies  or  the 
records  of  others,  to  work  them  into  a  coherent  picture, 
which   may  give   those   who   follow   some  idea   of    the 
peculiar  manner  in  which  our  age  looked  upon  the  world 
and  life,  how  it  intellectualised  and  spiritualised  them. 
This  attempt  is  therefore  not  a  history  of  outward  politi- 
cal changes  or  of  industrial  achievements  :  the  former  will 
probably  be  better  known  to  our  children  than  they  have        21. 

Not  a  politi- 

been  to  us ;  the  latter  will  soon  be  forgotten  as  such,  or  cai  history, 

nor  a  history 

incorporated  in  the  still  greater  results  of  the  future,  for  LutriTure' 
which  they  will  be  the  preparation.     Nor  is  it  a  history  and  Artt 
of  Knowledge  and  Science,  of  Literature  and  Art,  which 
I  purpose  to  write ;  though  as  these  are  the  outcome  of 
the  inner  life,  and  contain  it,  so  to  say,  in  a  crystallised 
form,  they  will  always  have  to  be  appealed  to  for  the 
purpose  of  verifying  the  conclusions  which  we  may  arrive 


1  On  the  division  of  History  into 
centuries  see  what  Du  Bois-Rey- 
mond  says  ('Reden,'  Leipzig,  1886, 
vol.  i.  p.  519),  and  the  fuller  dis- 
cussion of  the  subject  by  Prof.  O. 
Lorenz,  '  Die  Geschichts  -  wissen- 
schaft'  (Berlin,  1886,  p.  279  sqq.) 
The  latter  refers  to  what  the  first 
historian  says  (Herodotus,  ii.  142  : 
KCUTOI  rpir)Koffiat  fj.tv  avtiptav  yevfal 
Svvfarai  nvpia  Urea  •  yfvfal  yhp  rpfls 
avtipcev  e/caTdf  end  tan).  A  per- 
son born  in  1840  can  claim  to  have 
a  personal  knowledge  of  the  last 


half,  and  through  his  parents  and 
teachers  a  knowledge  of  the  first 
half,  of  the  century.  In  this  way 
it  may  be  said  that  his  personal — 
direct  or  indirect — knowledge  ex- 
tends over  nearly  a  century.  Lor- 
enz says  correctly  :  "  Fur  jeden 
einzelnen  bildet  der  Vater  und  der 
Sohn  eine  greifbare  Kette  von 
Lebensereignissen  und  Erfahrun- 
gen."  And  that  this  applies  even 
more  to  ideas  and  opinions,  to 
Thought,  than  to  events  and  facts, 
is  evident. 


14 


INTRODUCTION. 


22. 

Where  the 


which 
onr 


23. 

The  personal 

knowledge 


sary  for  a 


24. 

American 

influence 

only 

touched 


at.  What  will  interest  us  most  will  be  the  conscious 
aims  and  ends,  if  such  existed,  of  any  political  or  social 
movement,  and,  where  they  did  not  exist,  at  least  the 
results  to  our  inner  life  which  have  necessarily  followed, 
the  methods  by  which  knowledge  was  extended  or  science 
applied,  the  principles  which  underlay  literary  composition 
and  criticism,  and  the  hidden  spiritual  treasure  which 
poetry,  art,  and  religious  movements  aimed  at  revealing 
or  communicating  ;  in  fact  the  question  :  What  part  has 
the  inner  world  of  Thought  played  in  the  history  of  our 
century,  —  what  development,  what  progress,  what  gain 
has  been  the  result  of  the  external  events  and  changes  ? 
But  if  personal  knowledge  and  experience  are  —  as  it 
seems  to  me  —  of  the  greatest  importance  in  an  attempt 
\fee  this  :  if,  without  having  lived  the  inner  life,  a  record 
°^  &  would  be  either  a  mere  string  of  names  or  a  criticism 
of  opinions,  not  a  living  picture,  —  so  it  is  also  the  factor 
which  necessarily  limits  the  extent  of  the  ground  which 
I  propose  to  traverse.  Thus  I  feel  obliged  in  the  first 
place  to  limit  myself  to  European  Thought.  Such  a  limi- 
tation would  hardly  have  been  called  for  a  century  ago, 
because  it  would  have  been  a  matter  of  course  :  but  the 
steady  growth  and  peculiar  civilisation  of  a  new  and 
vigorous  people  on  the  other  side  of  the  Atlantic  force 
from  me  the  twofold  confession,  that  there  is  a  large 
world  of  growing  importance  of  which  I  have  no  personal 
knowledge,  and  to  estimate  which  I  therefore  feel  un- 
qualified and  unprepared  ;  and  further,  that  I  am  equally 
unable  to  picture  to  myself  the  aspect  which  the  whole  of 
our  European  culture  in  its  present  state  may  assume  to 
an  outside  and  far-removed  observer  who  is  placed  in  the 


INTRODUCTION.  15 

New  World.  As  this  New  World  grows  not  only  in 
numbers  and  national  wealth,  but  also  in  mental  depth, 
as  it  becomes  more  and  more  intellectualised  and 
spiritualised,  so  it  will  no  doubt  experience  the  desire  of 
recording  its  own  inner  life  and  culture,  emphasising  the 
peculiarities  which  distinguish  it  as  a  whole  from  our 
civilisation.  But  the  tendencies  of  this  new  culture  are 
to  rne  vague  and  enigmatical,  and  I  frankly  admit  that 
I  am  unable  to  say  anything  definite  on  this  subject.  Con- 
vinced as  I  am  that  in  human  affairs  all  outer  life  is  the 
vessel  which  contains  an  inner  substance,  the  shell  which 
envelops  a  growing  kernel,  I  am,  nevertheless,  unable  in 
this  case  to  penetrate  to  either,  and  must  therefore  content 
myself  with  taking  notice  of  this  vast  new  element  of 
nineteenth-century  culture  only  where  it  comes  into 
immediate  contact  with  European  thought,  which  has 
indeed  been  powerfully  influenced  by  it.  And  of  Euro-  25. 

OnlyFrench, 

pean  thought  itself  I  am  forced  to  select  likewise  only  German, 

J    and  English 

the  central  portion,  the  thought  embodied  in  French, 
German,  and  English  Literature.  I  have  to  admit  that 
Italian,  Scandinavian,  and  Eussian  influences  are  all 
around  this  centre,  sometimes  penetrating  far  into  it ; 
but  here  again  languages  unknown  and  interests  foreign 
to  me  have  made  it  impossible  to  identify  myself  ever  so 
superficially  with  the  new  life  that  is  contained  in  them. 
I  must  therefore  here  also  confine  myself  to  very  im- 
perfect and  casual  notices,  which  make  no  attempt  to 
do  justice  to  the  subject. 

The  subject  before  us,  then,  is  European  Thought — i.e., 
the  thought  of  France,  Germany,  and  England — during  the 
greater  part  of  the  nineteenth  century.  Circumscribed  as 


16 


INTRODUCTION. 


26. 

Unity  of 
Thought  a 
product 
of  this 
century. 


27. 
Voltaire. 


Adam 
Smith. 


this  subject  is  by  the  limits  of  time  and  space  which  I 
have  mentioned,  it  is,  nevertheless,  still  vast,  intricate,  and 
bewildering.  And  yet  it  is  my  intention,  throughout  the 
inquiries  which  I  have  to  institute  and  in  the  various  out- 
lines and  sketches  which  I  have  to  draw,  never  to  lose 
sight  of  the  unity  of  the  whole.  This  unity,  I  maintain, 
the  progress  of  our  age  has  more  and  more  forced  upon 
us.  It  is  itself  a  result  of  the  work  of  the  century.  A 
hundred  years — even  fifty  years — ago,  it  would  have  been 
impossible  to  speak  of  European  Thought  in  the  manner 
in  which  I  do  now.  For  the  seventeenth  and  eighteenth 
centuries  mark  the  period  in  which,  owing  to  the  use  of 
the  several  vernacular  languages  of  Europe  in  the  place 
of  the  mediaeval  Latin,  thought  became  nationalised,  in 
which  there  grew  up  first  the  separate  literature  and  then 
the  separate  thought  of  the  different  civilised  countries  of 
Western  Europe.  Thus  it  was  that  in  the  last  century, 
and  at  the  beginning  of  this,  people  could  make  journeys 
of  exploration  in  the  region  of  thought  from  one  country 
to  another,  bringing  home  with  them  new  and  fresh  ideas. 
Such  journeys  of  discovery,  followed  by  importation  of  new 
ideas,  were  those  of  Voltaire1  to  England  in  1726,  where 
he  found  the  philosophy  of  Newton  and  Locke,  at  that 
time  not  known  and  therefore  not  popularly  appreciated 
in  France;  the  journey  of  Adam  Smith  in  1765  to  France, 
where  he  became  acquainted  with  the  economic  system  of 
Quesnay  and  the  opinions  of  the  so-called  "  physiocrats," 
which  formed  the  starting-point  of  his  own  great  work, 


1  For  a  most  complete  collection 
of  data  referring  to  this  subject 
see  Du  Bois-Reymond's  address  in 


the  Berlin  Academy,  30th  January 
1868,  reprinted  in  the  collection  of 
his  'Reden,'  Leipzig,  1886,  vol.  i. 


INTRODUCTION.  17 

'  The  Wealth  of  Nations.'  During  the  last  quarter  of  the 
eighteenth  century  A.  G-.  Werner  raised  the  Mining 
Academy  at  Freiberg,  which  had  been  founded  in  1*766, 
from  a  mere  provincial  institution  to  be  one  of  the  great 
centres  of  scientific  light  in  Europe,  to  which  students 
from  all  parts  of  the  world  flocked  to  listen  to  his  eloquent 
teaching.  Towards  the  end  of  the  century  Wordsworth 
and  Coleridge  went  on  a  trip  to  Germany,  whence  the  29. 
latter  brought  to  England  the  new  philosophy  of  Kant  thought 

brought  to 

and  Schelling.     Madame  de  Stael,  in  an  age  when  tidings  coigeridgeby 
of  a  new  literary  life  in  Germany  had  reached  French  ^orto.0^3 
Society  through  some  of  the  emigrants  of  the  Kevolution, 
set  herself  reluctantly  to  learn  German,1  convinced  that  a       so. 
new  phase  of  thought  had  appeared  there  ;  and  then  with  thought 

imported 

Benjamin  Constant  visited  the  country  itself  at  the  end 


of  1  8  0  3  ,  and  again  in  1  8  0  7.  The  result  of  these  journeys  de  staa 
of  exploration  was  her  work  '  De  L'Allemagne.'  Whilst 
Coleridge  and  Madame  de  Stael  drew  inspiration  from 
the  new  life  which  centred  in  the  Weimar  of  Goethe  and 
Schiller,  the  scientific  students  of  the  whole  Continent 
directed  their  gaze  to  Paris,  where  alone  for  many  de- 
cades the  modern  methods  could  be  learnt,  where  the 
new  scientific  ideas  were,  so  to  speak,  collected  in  a  focus.  si 

Paris  the 

For  more  than  half  a  century  Paris  remained  the  centre  focus  »f 

scientific 

of  scientific  thought,2  and  even  English  philosophers,  who  ideas- 


1  See    Lady    Blennerhasset's   in-  j    dern  scheint,  jetzt  bei  Deutschland 
teresting  work  on  Madame  de  Stael,  angelangt  ist." 
German   ed.,  vol.  ii.  p.  461  sqq.  ;  \       2  See  Bruhns, 'Life  of  A.  v.  Hum- 
especially  the   remarkable   passage  boldt,'  translated  by  Lassell,  vol.  i. 


quoted  there,  p.  465,  in  her  letter 
to  the  Baron  de  Gerando,  October 


p.     232  :     "  Notwithstanding    the 
sardonic  expression  of  the  frantic 


1802:   "  Ich  glaube  wie   Sie,    dass       judge,  'Nous  u'avons  pas  besoin  de 
der  menschliche  Geist,  der  zu  wan-       savans,'  Paris  was  yet  at  the  close 

VOL.  I.  B 


18 


INTRODUCTION. 


3-2. 
Continental 


cal  methods 
introduced 
into  Eng- 
land by 
Babbmge, 
BtndML 
ar.1  Pea- 
cock. 


33. 


34. 

Comte's 
philosophy 
shown  to  his 
own  country 
by  an  Eng- 


since  Bacon  and  Xewton  had  followed  their  own  inde- 
pendent line  of  research,  had  to  discover  in  the  second 
decade  of  the  century  that  Xewton's  great  name  was  not 
a  guarantee  for  the  efficiency  of  his  methods,  which  had 
been  greatly  developed  and  improved  in  the  hands  of 
Continental  mathematicians.  These  improved  methods 
were  imported  into  England  by  three  Cambridge  grad- 
uates, Herschel,  Babbage,  and  Peacock,  who  translated 
Lacroix's  Treatise,  and  by  doing  so  gave  a  great  impetus 
to  mathematical  research  in  this  country.  Fifteen  years 
later,  students  from  all  parts  of  the  world  flocked  to  the 
small  University  town  of  Giessen  in  Germany,  thence  to 
take  home  with  them  a  knowledge  of  the  new  science  and 
methods  of  Chemistry,  taught  in  the  laboratory  of  Liebig — 
methods  previously  used  only  in  the  private  and  inacces- 
sible laboratories  of  learned  investigators.1  It  will  be  in 
the  memory  of  many  how  the  philosophy  of  Auguste 
Comte,  published  between  the  years  1830  and  1840, 
remained  without  much  influence  in  his  own  country, 
whereas,  mainly  through  the  writings  of  J.  S.  Mill  and 


of  the  eighteenth  century  the 
metropolis  of  the  exact  sciences. 
Lalaude,  in  writing  to  von  Zach  on 
January  26,  1798,  remarks:  'The 
love  of  mathematics  is  daily  on 
the  increase,  not  only  with  us  but 
in  the  army.  The  result  of  this 
was  unmistakably  apparent  in  our 
last  campaigns.  Bonaparte  himself 
has  a  mathematical  head,  and  though 
all  who  study  this  science  may  not 
become  geometricians  like  Laplace 
and  Lagrange,  or  heroes  like  Bona- 
parte, there  is  yet  left  an  influence 
upon  the  mind  which  enables  them 
to  accomplish  more  than  they  could 
possibly  have  achieved  without  this 
training.  Our  mathematical  schools 


are  good,  and  successfully  accom- 
plish their  main  object  in  the 
diffusion  of  mathematical  know- 
ledge."' Compare  also  vol.  i.  p. 
342,  referring  to  1804.  Also  vol.  ii 
p.  92,  referring  to  the  period  1820 
to  1830.  "  Humboldt  continued 
to  regard  Paris  as  the  true  metro- 
polis of  Science  "  (p.  70' ,  and  many 
other  passages.  See  also  Steffens, 
"  Was  ich  erlebte,"  vol.  x.  p.  233, 
and  what  Goethe  said  to  Eckermann 
on  the  contrast  of  Germany  and 
Paris  in  the  year  1S27. 

1  See  A.  'W.  Hoffmann.  "The 
life  -  Work  of  Liebig,'  Faraday 
Lecture  for  1875,  p.  8. 


INTRODUCTION.  1 9 

his  school,  it  became,  as  it  were,  a  centre  of  thought,  an 
embodiment  of  a  circle  of  modern  ideas  in  this  country, 
whence  it  was  reimported  into  France  nearly  a  generation 
after  its  first  appearance.  Something  similar  happened 
to  a  once  neglected  but  now  renowned  English  landscape- 
painter,  Constable,  whose  pictures  when  exhibited  in  35. 
France  in  1824  created  a  profound  sensation,  and  had  influence  in 

France. 

such  an  influence  on  the  artists  of  that  country  that  they 
are  said  to  mark  an  era  in  landscape-painting  there.1 

Such  journeys  of  discovery  in  the  realm  of  thought  and 
ideas  have  now  become  almost  impossible.  In  the  course 
of  our  century  Science  at  least  has  become  international :  36. 

Science  be- 

isolated  and  secluded  centres   of   thought  have  become  c°n?e  inter- 
national. 

more  and  more  rare.  Intercourse,  periodicals,  and  learned 
societies  with  their  meetings  and  reports,'  proclaim  to  the 
whole  world  the  minutest  discoveries  and  the  most  recent 
developments.  National  peculiarities  still  exist,  but  are 
mainly  to  be  sought  in  those  remoter  and  more  hidden 
recesses  of  thought,  where  the  finer  shades,  the  untrans- 
latable idioms,  of  language  suggest,  rather  than  clearly 
express,  a  struggling  but  undefined  idea.  Thought  has  its 
dawn  and  twilight,  its  chiaroscuro  as  well  as  its  open  day  ; 
but  the  daylight  has  grown  wider  and  clearer  and  more  dif- 


1  See  Walter  Armstrong  in  the 
'  Nineteenth  Century '  for  April 
1887  ;  Julius  Meyer,  '  Geschichte 
der  modernen  frauzosischen  Mal- 
erei,'  Leipzig,  1867,  Book  7,  chap. 
2 ;  A.  Rosenberg,  '  Geschichte  der 
modernen  Kunst,'  vol.  i.  p.  63. 
Rosenberg  thinks  the  influence  of 
Constable  on  French  Art  is  exagger- 
ated, and  mentions  Paul  Huet, 
whose  early  pictures  date  from 
1822.  But  an  Englishman,  Bon- 
ington,  who,  however,  is  claimed  as 


of  the  French  School,  was  even 
before  Huet  and  Constable.  See 
also  what  Delacroix  wrote  to  Th. 
Sylvestre  in  1858  :  "  Constable  est 
une  des  gloires  anglaises.  C'est  un 
veritable  re"formateur,  sorti  de  1'or- 
niere  des  paysagistes  anciens.  Notre 
ecole  a  grandement  profite"  de  ses 
examples  et  Gdricault  e"tait  revenu 
tout  etourdi  de  1'un  des  grands  pay- 
sages  qu'il  nous  avait  envoyes " 
(quoted  by  Emile  Michel  in  '  Grande 
Encyclopedic,'  art.  "Constable"). 


20 


INTRODUCTION. 


37. 

The  light 
which  Ety- 
mology 
throws  on 
history  of 
Thought, 


38. 

and  on  the 
migration 
of  ideas. 


fused  in  the  course  of  our  century,  and  so  far  as  the  greater 
volume  of  ideas  is  concerned,  we  can  speak  now  of  Euro- 
pean thought,  when  at  one  time  we  should  have  had  to 
distinguish  between  French,  German,  and  English  thought. 
Reserving,  therefore,  in  the  meantime  the  task  of  investi- 
gating what  still,  within  the  bounds  of  this  larger  inter- 
national life,  remains  peculiar  to  the  thought  of  each 
nation,  it  is  the  great  body  of  common  European  thought 
with  which  I  propose  at  first  to  deal.  How  has  it  grown 
to  be  what  it  is  now,  what  special  contributions  have  the 
several  nations  made  to  the  general  stock,  what  is  at 
present  our  inventory  of  it,  how  has  it  been  changed  in 
course  of  the  century  ?  But  how,  it  may  be  asked,  are  we 
to  take  stock  ?  how  is  this  inventory  to  be  drawn  up  ? 
There  is  indeed  one  very  obvious  method  which  presents 
itself,  though  it  is  not  the  one  which  I  propose  to  use 
exclusively,  or  even  largely.  And  yet  it  seems  to  me 
well  worthy  of  special  attention. 

Already  I  have  remarked  how  the  changes  of  thought 
are  deposited  in  the  altered  language  and  style  of  the 
age.  A  closer  study  of  the  changes  which,  in  the  course  of 
this  century,  have  taken  place  in  the  vocabularies  as  well 
as  in  the  styles  of  the  three  principal  European  languages 
would  no  doubt  reveal  to  a  great  extent  when  and  how 
new  ideas  have  presented  themselves,  how  they  have 
become  fixed  and  defined  in  special  words  or  terms.  It 
would  allow  us  to  trace  to  a  very  large  extent  not  only 
the  growth  of  the  general  stock  of  European  thought,  but 
also  the  migration  of  single  ideas  from  one  nation  to 
another.  And,  lastly,  it  would  exhibit  to  a  great  extent 
in  what  peculiar  phrases,  in  what  secluded  corners,  the 


INTRODUCTION. 


21 


individual  thought  of  each  of  the  three  nations  has  found 
refuge.1  Any  one  who  has  attempted  to  translate  from 
one  of  these  languages  into  another,  be  it  prose  or  be 
it  lyrical,  philosophical,  or  descriptive  poetry,  will  have 
experienced  the  necessity  of  studying  minutely  the 
meaning  or  hidden  thought  which  a  word  or  a  phrase 
may  signify :  he  will  have  been  led  to  notice  what  is 
common  and  what  is  peculiar  to  different  languages, 


1  The  only  books  which  treat 
of  words  in  the  sense  mentioned 
above,  and  which  have  come  under 
my  notice,  are  Home  Tooke's  '  Di- 
versions of  Purley  '  and  Archbishop 
Trench's  little  volumes  on  '  The 
Study  of  Words '  and  '  English 
Past  and  Present.'  So  far  as  the 
use  of  merely  philosophical  terms 
is  concerned,  I  may  refer  to  R. 
Eucken,  '  Geschichte  der  philoso- 
phischen  Terminologie,'  Leipzig, 
1879.  A  great  deal  of  material 
for  a  research  of  this  kind  may 
be  found  in  the  large  Dictionaries 
of  Grimm,  Littre,  and  Murray, 
though  I  do  not  feel  sure  that  the 
great  change  which  has  come  over 
language,  through  the  expansion, 
deepening,  and  differentiation  of 
ideas  and  of  thought  in  our  age, 
has  been  specially  taken  note  of. 
The  plan  of  Grimm's  Dictionary, 
which  aims  at  embracing  the  Ger- 
man language  in  its  development 
during  three  centuries,  beginning 
with  Luther  and  ending  with 
Goethe  (see  Wilh.  Grimm's '  Kleinere 
Schriften,'  vol.  i.  p.  508),  almost 
excludes  the  period  which  I  am 
reviewing. 

It  is  interesting  to  remember 
that  Diderot,  the  first  writer  who 
attempted  to  collect  the  great  body 
of  modern  Thought  and  Learning 
into  an  encyclopaedic  whole,  re- 
ferred to  Language  very  much  in 
the  same  manner  as  we  do  now, 
a.  hundred  and  fifty  years  later. 


See  the  article  "Encyclopedic," 
where  Diderot  says  that  a  Dic- 
tionary is  only  an  exact  collection 
of  titles,  to  be  filled  in  by  the  Ency- 
clopaedia ;  and  further  on,  p.  639  : 
"Si  1'on  compte  les  hommes  de 
ge"nie,  et  qu'on  les  re"pande  sur 
toute  la  duree  des  siecles  ecoules, 
il  est  evident  qu'ils  seront  en  petit 
nombre  dans  chaque  nation  et  pour 
chaque  siecle,  et  qu'on  n'en  trouvera 
presqu'aucun  qui  n'ait  perfectionnd 
la  langue.  Les  hommes  cre"ateurs 
portent  ce  caractere  particulier. 
Comme  ce  n'est  pas  seulement  en 
feuilletant  les  productions  de  leur 
contemporains  qu'ils  rencontrent 
les  ide"es  qu'ils  ont  a  employer  dans 
leurs  ecrits,  mais  que  c'est  tantot  en 
descendant  profonde"ment  en  eux- 
memes,  tantot  en  s'elancant  au 
dehors,  et  portantdes  regards  plus 
attentifs  et  plus  pene"trans  sur  les 
natures  qu'ils  environnent,  ils  sont 
obliges,  surtout  a  1'origine  des 
langues,  d'inventer  des  signes  pour 
rendre  avec  exactitude  et  avec  force 
ce  qu'ils  y  decouvrent  les  premiers. 
C'est  la  chaleur  de  1'imagination  et 
la  meditation  profonde  qui  enrichis- 
sent  une  langue  d'expressions  nou- 
velles  :  c'est  la  justesse  de  1'esprit 
et  la  seVerite"  de  la  dialectique  qui 
en  perfectionnent  la  syntaxe  ;  c'est 
la  commodity  des  organes  de  la 
parole  qui  1'adoucit;  c'est  la  sen- 
sibilite"  de  1'oreille  qui  la  rend  har- 
monieuse." 


22 


INTRODUCTION. 


39. 

Goethe. 


40. 

Peculiarity 
of  the 
German 
Language. 


41. 

Growth  in 
the  mean- 
ings of 
words. 


and  the  thought  which  they  express.  Of  Goethe  it 
may  be  said  that  he  created  to  a  large  extent  the 
language  and  style  of  that  which  is  best  in  the  modern 
literature  of  his  country.  No  such  supreme  influence 
belonging  to  a  single  individual  can  probably  be  found 
in  any  other  German,  French,  or  English  writer  in  our 
century,  for  reasons  which  are  obvious :  but  the  great 
French  novelists,  the  German  metaphysicians,  and  the 
original  poetical  minds  of  modern  England  have  en- 
larged and  enriched  the  vocabulary  of  their  respec- 
tive languages,  and  have  added  a  number  of  useful 
and  novel  modes  of  expression  (toumures,  Wendungen). 
Carlyle's  influence  has  been  great  in  introducing  novel 
epithets,  borrowed  or  imported  frequently  from  the 
German.  Matthew  Arnold  has  laboured  in  a  similar 
direction,  his  models  being,  besides  Goethe  and  Heine, 
mostly  French  authors,  such  as  Sainte-Beuve  and  the 
introspective  school.  Germany  has  been  less  fortunate 
in  extending  her  vernacular  vocabulary :  the  facility 
which  her  language  possesses  of  assimilating  foreign  words 
and  using  them  almost  without  any  alteration  has  done 
much  to  complicate  German  style,  destroying  its  sim- 
plicity, its  graces,  the  poetical  element.  It  will,  however, 
probably  be  found  that  by  far  the  greatest  accession  to 
the  vocabularies — though  not  to  the  finer  modelling — of 
the  modern  languages  has  come  from  the  influence  of  the 
sciences  on  general  culture  and  literature.  "Well-known 
words,  long  in  use,  have  at  the  same  time  through  this 
influence  acquired  altered  or  more  specific  meanings. 

The  vaguer  word  "  development "  has  been  supplanted 
by  "  evolution."     "  Differentiation  "  has  a  definite  philo- 


INTRODUCTION.  23 

sophic — not  only  a  mathematical — meaning.  The  word 
"  positive  "  has,  besides  the  logical  signification,  acquired 
at  least  two  meanings  which  are  very  specific,  and 
which  it  did  not  possess  formerly.  "  Energy "  has, 
besides  the  general  meaning,  and  the  philosophical  one 
which  Aristotle  assigned  to  it,  acquired  a  special  meaning, 
having  first  in  England  and  then  abroad  taken  the  place 
of  "  force "  as  a  more  correct  and  definable  term.  In 
connection  with  it,  "  correlation  "  and  "  conservation  "  are 
terms  of  very  specific  value.  The  word  "fittest"  and  the 
phrase  "  struggle  for  existence  "  mean  something  different 
from  what  they  meant  fifty  years  ago.  Then  there  are  42. 

New 

the  terms  "exact"  and  "science"  themselves,  which  mean  thought 

has  found 

something  different  now  from  what  they  meant  formerly.  new  words- 

And  coming  out  of  the  more  recent  doctrines  of  the  limits 

of  human  and  conscious  individual  knowledge,  there  are 

the  words  "  unconscious,"  "  unknowable,"  and  "  agnostic," 

which  indicate  whole  trains  of  novel  thought.      It  would 

indeed  be  an  interesting  and  useful  investigation  to  follow 

up  to>  their  origin  the  many  new  words  and  phrases,  or 

the  altered  meanings  of  well-known  and  familiar  words, 

in  which  the  three  principal  European  languages  abound. 

It  would  be  a  methodical  study  of  the  changes  which 

thought  has  undergone. 

Nor  need  such  an  undertaking  be  based  upon  any 
particular  or  one-sided  theory  as  to  the  connection  of 
Civilisation,  Thought,  and  Language.  This  century  has  43. 

De  Bonald's 

not  been  wanting  in  such,  from  the  extreme  theory  of  theory  of 

revealed 

De  Bonald,1  who  saw  in  Language  an  immediate  Divine  ^Maf 
revelation,  to  the  most  recent  and  more  scientific  view  sciencVof 

Language. 
1  De  Bonald  (1754-1840),  '  Legislation  primitive,'  Paris,  1802. 


24  INTRODUCTION. 

of  Max  Miiller,  who  would  absorb  philosophy  in  the 
science  of  Language l  in  the  same  way  as  Astronomy  has 
to  many  become  merely  "  une  question  d'analyse."  In  a 
certain  sense  we  can  agree  with  both  of  these  thinkers. 
Without  discussing  the  vexed  question  of  the  origin  of 
Language  and  Thought,  to  us  as  individuals,  born  in  a 
civilised  and  intellectual  age,  words  certainly  came  earlier 
than  clear  and  conscious  thought.  The  easy  manner  also  in 
which,  through  the  use  of  our  parents'  tongue,  we  became 
introduced  into  a  complex  and  bewildering  labyrinth  of 
highly  abstract  reasoning  is  little  short  of  a  miraculous 
revelation.  But,  as  I  mentioned  above,  it  is  not  my 
intention  to  study  the  development  of  European  thought 
during  this  century  by  means  of  a  close  analysis  of  the 
changes  and  growth  of  the  three  principal  languages. 
Such  an  enterprise  would  demand  an  amount  of  lexico- 
graphical knowledge  possessed  only  by  the  authors  of 
dictionaries  like  those  of  Grimm,  Littre,  and  Murray. 
But  though  I  am  not  qualified  for  such  a  task,  there  is  one 
special  point  on  which  I  cannot  avoid  being  drawn  into 
a  grammatical  discussion.  It  refers  to  the  word  Thought 
44.  itself.  How  is  the  meaning  which  I  and  my  readers  con- 

Tbought, 

bo*  ex-       nect  with  this  word  to  be  expressed  in  French  and  Ger- 

pressed  in  ^ 

JS^L114  man  ?  E°w  are  we  to  translate  the  word  ?  The  subject  we 
deal  with  does  not  belong  to  England  alone,  but  as  much 
to  France  and  to  Germany :  it  must  thus  have  a  name  in 
each  of  their  languages.  Now  I  believe  that  the  word 
penste  expresses  in  French  very  nearly  the  same  thing 
which  we  mean  in  English  by  thought.  It  is  sorne- 

1  See  his  '  Science  of  Thought, '  London,  1 887,  especially  pp.  292  and 
550. 


INTRODUCTION. 


25 


what  more  difficult  to  find  a  corresponding  word  in  Ger- 
man. I  have  for  some  time  hesitated  whether  to  use  the 
word  Gfeist  or  Weltanschauung,  two  terms  frequently  used 
to  express  the  aggregate  of  the  inner  life  of  an  age :  but 
have  finally  resolved  to  use  the  word  Denken,  as  this  word 
lends  itself  to  the  same  contrasts  of  Life  and  Action 
(Leben  und  Handeln),  denoting  the  inner  world,  whereas 
the  opposite  of  Geist  is  Stoff  (matter),  and  Weltanschauung, 
though  an  expressive  and  untranslatable  word,  denotes 
rather  the  outcome,  the  result,  of  thought  than  thought 
itself.  Passing  from  the  word  to  the  subject  itself,  I  find 
that  the  greater  definiteness  of  the  term  in  the  English 
language  is  accompanied  also  by  a  more  abundant  litera- 
ture of  the  subject.  The  larger  idea  of  a  Philosophy  of  45. 

History  is  indeed  due  mainly  to  Continental  thinkers,  of  History 

due  to  con- 
especially    to    Herder,   Hegel,   Comte,  and    Guizot,  and  ^^ 

Voltaire's  '  Siecle  de  Louis  XIV.'  will  always  be  the 
model  of  the  historical  picture  of  a  period.  Still  it  is — 
in  my  opinion — mainly  the  writings  of  Carlyle,  Buckle, 
Draper,  Lecky,  Leslie  Stephen,  and,  considering  its  size, 
perhaps  more  than  all,  Mark  Pattison's  '  Essay,'1  which 
have  fixed  in  our  minds  the  meaning  of  the  word 
Thought  as  the  most  suitable  and  comprehensive  term 
to  denote  the  whole  of  the  inner  or  hidden  Life  and 
Activity  of  a  period  or  a  nation.  I  therefore  put  in  a 
claim  to  start  with  the  use  of  the  English  word,  as 
sufficiently  familiar  to  most  of  my  readers,  and  request 
those  who  may  object  to  the  vagueness  of  the  French 


1  See  '  Essays  and  Reviews,' 
'  Tendencies  of  Religious  Thought 
in  England,  1688-1750,'  by  Mark 
Pattison ;  also  Leslie  Stephen's 


remarks  on  it  in  the  Preface  to 
his  'History  of  English  Thought 
in  the  Eighteenth  Century. ' 


26  INTRODUCTION. 

and  German  equivalents  to  look  for  a  definition  of  my 
intention  in  the  English  word  "  Thought."  I  am  not 
aware  that  French  literature  possesses  any  "  histoire  de 
la  pensee,"  either  of  a  longer  or  shorter  period ;  I  know 
of  innumerable  works  in  German  which  cover  a  similar 
field,  but  they  have  mostly  used  the  word  Weltanschauung, 
or  expanded  the  meaning  of  Thought  into  the  wider  sense 
of  a  history  of  Civilisation  (Kulturgeschichte)  or  narrowed 
,  it  to  that  of  Literature,  proving — as  it  seems  to  me — 

46.  the  real  want  of  a  concise  term  such  as  the  English 

Want  of 

FnGemln™11  language  now  supplies.     And  yet,  I  think  I  am.  right 

and  French.  jn  saving  that  the  conception  of  Thought,  in  the  sense 

in  which  I  am  using  it,  is  truly  an  outcome  of  interna- 

47.  tional,  not  of  specifically  English  progress,  and  belongs 
De^thf.1111    mainly  to  the  period  of  which  I  am  treating, — a  period 
cmscaity8pe"  characterised,  as  I  have  already  remarked,  by  the  great 

interchange  of  ideas,  by  the  breaking  down  of  intellectual 
barriers,  between   the   principal   European  nationalities. 

48.  It  was  above  all  in  the  mind  of  Thomas  Carlyle,  who  first 

Carlyle  the  J 

a?peciafve  among  Englishmen  made  a  profound  study  of  the  intel- 
tTeTord*0  lectual  agencies  which  brought  about  the  great  change  in 
modern  Europe,  that  the  conception  formed  itself  of  an 
intellectual  and  spiritual  organism,  underlying  and  moving 
external  events.  He  first  gave  the  peculiar  sense  to  the 
word  Thought,  in  which  we  here  employ  it,  and  made  it 
an  object  of  special  study  for  those  who  came  after  him ; 
an  object,  indeed,  definable  in  various  ways  and  to  be  con- 
templated from  differing  points  of  view,  but  yet  a  some- 
thing, a  power  recognised  by  every  one,  and  for  which  no 
better  word  could  be  invented.  No  other  language  has  a. 
word  so  comprehensive,  denoting  at  once  the  process  and 


INTRODUCTION.  27 

the  result,  the  parts  and  the  ideal  whole,  of  what  is  felt 
and  meant :  it  commits  us  to  no  preconceived  theory, 
can  be  used  equally  by  thinkers  of  the  most  opposite 
views,  and  lends  itself  to  any  specialisation  which  may 
become  necessary. 


II. 


Two   processes  have  helped  to  determine  the   intel-        i. 

r  The  two 

lectual  progress  of  mankind.  These  two  processes  have  f^g 
often  been  apparently  opposed  to  each  other  in  their 
operations ;  but  in  reality  neither  of  them  can  proceed 
very  far  without  calling  the  other  into  existence.  They 
are  the  extension  and  the  condensation  of  knowledge. 
Curiosity,  the  demands  of  practical  life,  the  experiences 
of  every  day,  all  tend  to  an  enlargement,  to  an  accumula- 
tion of  knowledge.  Such  growing  knowledge  is,  however, 
of  little  avail  if  it  be  not  readily  grasped :  the  command 
of  knowledge  is  as  important  as  its  accumulation.  The 
more  extensive  the  country  which  we  wish  to  explore,  the 
more  we  look  out  for  elevated  and  commanding  points 
of  view,  which  permit  us  at  a  glance  to  overlook  a  wide 
landscape  measuring  the  distance  behind  or  the  prospect 
before  us.  But,  however  enticing,  these  elevated  views 
are  frequently  seductive  and  misleading.  They  permit  us 
not  only  to  look  backward  on  the  land  which  we  have 
explored,  giving  us  a  clearer  picture  of  its  many  features, 
of  its  winding  paths,  of  the  position  of  its  separate  objects 
— these  elevated  views  present  to  us  likewise  the  regions 
which  we  have  not  yet  explored,  and  suggest  the  attempt 
to  supersede  the  laborious  process  of  further  exploration 


28 


INTRODUCTION. 


by  the  more  delightful  venture  of  filling  up  the  dim  out- 
lines which  we  see  before  us,  with  analogies  of  past  ex- 
perience or  creations  of  our  imagination.  And  even  if 
we  do  descend  into  the  plains  and  continue  the  minuter 
and  more  laborious  search,  we  cannot  rid  ourselves  of  cer- 
tain preconceived  but  frequently  misleading  ideas  which 
the  superficial  glance  has  impressed  on  our  minds. 

The  condensation  may  become  an  idealisation  of  know- 
ledge. History  affords  numerous  examples  of  these  dif- 
ferent stages  of  progress  ;  centuries  of  dull  accumulation, 
of  unmethodical  and  ill-arranged  learning,  have  been  fol- 
lowed by  short  periods  of  enlightenment,  by  the  trium- 
phant shout  of  sudden  discovery  or  the  confident  hope  of 
invention.  Patient  work  and  real  progress  have  for  a  long 
time  been  repressed  by  the  allurements  of  seductive  phan- 
toms, which  have  had  to  be  abandoned  after  an  immense 
waste  of  labour.  New  prospects  have  suddenly  opened 
the  view  into  vast  unexplored  regions,  heights  have  been 
gained  from  which  the  whole  of  human  knowledge  ap- 
peared for  the  moment  condensed  into  a  single  truth  or 
idealised  into  a  vision,  and  again  these  delightful  achieve- 
ments have  for  a  time  appeared  lost  in  an  all-pervading 
discouragement  and  dismay. 

Whether  our  century  has  been  characterised  by  any 

J 

one  or  by  a  succession  of  several  of  these  varying  moods, 
is  a  question  which  I  hope  to  answer  in  the  sequel.     For 
the  present  it  is  sufficient  to  note  that  in  both  directions  — 
3         in  that  of  accumulating  and  in  that  of  condensing  and 
TOnte^-nun-  idealising  knowledge  —  the  efforts  of  the  nineteenth  cen- 
ueamnia-     tury  have  been  many  and  conspicuous.     In  the  former  it 

tion  of  . 

knowledge,    is  altogether  unparalleled,  whereas  in  the  latter  it  has 


2. 

Object  of 

the  book. 


INTRODUCTION.  29 

probably  not  equalled  the  ideal  greatness  of  Greece  in 
the  Periclean  age,  the  brilliancy  of  the  Eenaissance  in 
Italy,  or  the  great  discoveries  of  the  sixteenth  and  seven- 
teenth centuries  in  France  and  England.  But  what  our 
century  has  done  is  this  :  it  has  worked  out  and  deposited  4. 

Nineteenth 

in  special  terms  of  language  a  clearer  view  of  the  correct  ce,nttuTyi 

what  it  has 

methods  for  extending  knowledge,  and  a  peculiar  concep-  ^Meth^i 
tion  of  its  possible  unity.     At  one  time  —  and  that  not 


.  very  long  ago  —  the  word  truth  seemed  to  indicate  to  the  iedge. 
seeker  not  only  the  right  method  and  road  for  attaining 
knowledge,  but  also  the  end,  the  crown  of  knowledge. 
"  Truth,  and  nothing  but  truth,"  seems  still  to  the  popular 
mind  the  right  maxim  for  seeking  knowledge  —  the  whole 
truth  stands  before  it  as  the  unity  of  all  knowledge,  were 
it  found.  I  think  it  is  now  sufficiently  clear  to  the  scien-  5. 

.  Search  after 

tmc  inquirer,  as  well  as  to  the  philosopher,  that  love  of  truth  not 

the  end  of 

truth,  while  it  does  indeed  denote  the  moral  attitude  of  the 


inquiring  mind,  is  insufficient  to  define  either  the  path  or  th^fnquh-- 
the  end  of  knowledge.  "  What  is  truth  ?  "  is  still  the  un-  IB 
solved  question.  The  criteria  of  truth  are  still  unsettled. 
It  would,  indeed,  be  a  sorrowful  experience,  a  calamity  of 
unparalleled  magnitude,  if  ever  the  moral  ideas  of  truth 
and  faith  should  disappear  out  of  the  soul  of  either  the 
active  worker  or  the  inquiring  thinker;  but  it  is  with 
these  as  with  other  treasures  of  our  moral  nature,  such  as 
goodness  and  holiness,  beauty  and  poetry  —  our  knowledge 
of  them  does  not  begin,  nor  does  it  increase,  by  definition  ; 
and  though  in  the  unthinking  years  of  our  childhood  we 
acquire  and  appropriate  these  moral  possessions  through 
the  words  of  our  mother-tongue,  they  rarely  gain  in  depth 
or  meaning  by  logical  distinctions  which  we  may  learn, 


30  INTRODUCTION. 

or  to  which  we  have  to  submit,  in  later  life.  These  do 
not  touch  the  essence,  though  very  frequently  they  may 
succeed  in  destroying  the  depth,  of  our  convictions. 

In  the  place,  then,  of  the  high-sounding  but  indefinable 

search  after  truth,  modern  science  has  put  an  elaborate 

e.        method  of  inquiry:  this  method  has  to  be  learnt  by  patient 

Method  of 

scientific      practice,  and  not  by  listening  to  a  description  of  it.      It  is 
]£^byed      laid  down  in  the  works  of  those  modern  heroes  of  science, 
Newton,**.,  from  Galileo  and  Newton  onward,  who  have  practised  it 
Bacon,         successfully,  and  from  whose  writings  philosophers  from 
Mm,  &c.      Bacon  to  Comte  and  Mill  have — not  without  misunder- 
standing and  error — tried  to  extract  the  rationale.    These 
methods  will  take  up  a  large  portion  of  our  attention. 
For  the  moment  it  is  important  to  note  that  the  result  or 
aim  of  scientific  inquiry  does  not  dictate  the  methods, — the 
purely  scientific  inquirer  does  not  know  where  the  path 
will  lead  him :  it  is  sufficient  that  it  be  clearly  marked. 
Modern  science  defines  the  method,  not  the  aim,  of  its 
work.      It  is  based  upon  numbering  and  calculating — in 
short,  upon  mathematical  processes ;  and  the  progress  of 
science  depends  as  much  upon  introducing  mathematical 
notions  into  subjects  which  are  apparently  not  mathe- 
matical, as  upon  the  extension  of  mathematical  methods 
and  conceptions  themselves.    The  terms  "exact"  and  "posi- 
tive" are  current  in  the  Continental  and  English  languages 
to  denote  these  methods  and  their  application.     Now  to 
any  one  who  does  not  stand  in  the  midst  of  the  scientific 
work  of  the  age,  it  might  appear  as  if  by  merely  following 
Dismtegra-    a  defined  method  which  is  capable  of  numerous  modifica- 
learn'ing       tions, — by  treading  a  clear  path  which  in  its  course  leads 
parent.         us  to  endless  equally  defined  ramifications, — the  scientific 


INTRODUCTION.  31 

inquirer  is  losing  daily  more  and  more  those  elevated 
views,  those  points  of  condensation,  those  unifying  and 
idealising  aspects  on  which,  as  it  seems  to  us,  the  com- 
mand and  grasp  of  knowledge  depends.  This  is  indeed 
almost  inevitable  so  far  as  the  older  ideas  are  con- 
cerned. Unity  of  knowledge,  order  and  harmony,  even 
completeness  and  symmetry,  truth  and  beauty,  are  indeed 
no  longer  of  direct  use  as  canons  for  the  scientific  inquirer, 
any  more  than  the  mysteries  once  supposed  to  be  inherent 
in  certain  numbers.  Though  we  still  live  under  the 
charm  of  such  entities,  however  much  we  may  try  to  get  rid 
of  them,  it  must  nevertheless  be  admitted  that  the  poetical, 
philosophical,  and  religious  aspects  of  things  seem  to  recede  s. 
into  an  increasing  distance  from  the  scientific  ;  they  do  not  distance 

between 

guide  scientific  search  ;  it  does  not  receive  from  them  much  ^j^ and 
support.  Have  both  sides  been  losers  by  this  change  ? 
So  far  as  science  is  concerned,  it  can  claim  to  have  attained 
by  it  not  only  a  greater  formal  completeness  and  certainty 
of  progress,  but  also  another  very  important  advantage 
which  was  unknown  to  ancient  and  mediaeval  research. 

This  advantage  consists  in  the  closer  connection  be-        9. 
tween  science  and  practical  life.     The  same  mathematical  nection 

between 

spirit  which  governs  scientific  methods  rules  also  in  trade,  science  and 
commerce,  and  industry,  and  is  gradually  penetrating  into 
the  professions,  such  as  medicine,  law,  and  administration. 
For  all  these  pursuits  have  either  directly  to  do  with 
numbers,  measures,  and  weights,  with  distances  of  space 
and  time,  or  they  have  found  it  necessary  to  introduce 
an  elaborate  system  of  statistics  and  averages  through 
which  the  irregularity  and  captiousness  of  subjective 
and  individual  influences  are  practically  eliminated.  The 


32  INTRODUCTION. 

problems  of  scientific  research  have  thus  enormously  in- 
creased ;  each  advance  in  science  increases  our  command 
of  certain  measurable  phenomena  in  practical  life  ;  each 
new  development  in  the  latter  prepares  a  new  field  for 
scientific  inquiry.  The  contact  between  science  and  life 
has  become  more  intimate  in  the  course  of  our  century. 
This  to  a  great  extent  has  counterbalanced  the  tendency 
of  modern  scientific  method,  which,  operating  alone,  would 
have  led  to  endless  specialisation  ;  for  it  is  the  peculiarity 

10.  of  all  practical  problems  that  they  cannot  be  isolated  in 

Solidarity  of  . 

aii  practical  the  same  way  as  scientific  experiments  —  that  they,  in  fact, 
force  upon  us  the  necessity  of  looking  at  a  large  number 
of  surrounding  and  extraneous  circumstances,  at  the  total- 
ity of  life  and  its  interests.1 

If  our  century  can  claim  to  have  firmly  established 
exact  or  positive  methods  in  science  and  life,  and  to  have 
furthered  in  this  way  the  interests  of  both,  the  question 

11.  remains,  Has  nothing  been  done  to  uphold  those  older, 

What  has  the 

nineteenth    those  time-hallowed  ideals  of  truth,  beauty,  and  wisdom 

century  •  ' 

which  to  former  ages  seemed  to  denote  the  unifying  and 


harmonising  principles  of  science  and  life  1  What  has 
become  of  philosophy,  art,  and  religion,  which  were  once 
intrusted  with  the  special  care  of  those  ideals,  charged 
with  preventing  the  falling  asunder  of  the  many  branches 
of  knowledge  and  practice,  and  expected  to  save  us  from 
a  loss  of  the  belief  in  the  integrity,  interdependence,  and 
co-operation  of  all  human  interests  ? 

1  Science  deals  with  things  in  the  i    In  this  distinction  lies  the  value  of 

abstract,  in  their  isolation,  in  vacua.  |   Lotze's  definition  of  the  reality  of 

Practical  life  deals  with  the  same  a  thing  as  "  a  standing  in  relation," 

things  in  their  position  in  the  real  viz.,  to  other  things,  to  all  things. 

world,  surrounded  by  other  things.  ;   See  'Microcosmus,'  book  ix. 


INTRODUCTION.  33 

Unless  I  believed  that  our  age  was  elaborating  a  deeper       12. 

Deeper  con- 

and  more  significant  conception  of  this  unity  of  all  human  ception  of 

the  unity 

interests,  of  the  inner  mental  life  of  man  and  mankind,  "n^"™^11 
I  do  not  think  I  should  have  deemed  it  worth  while  to 
write  the  following  volumes :  for  it  is  really  their  main 
end  and  principal  object  to  trace  the  co-operation  of  many 
agencies  in  the  higher  work  of  our  century ;  the  growing 
conviction  that  all  mental  efforts  combine  together  to 
produce  and  uphold  the  ideal  possessions  of  our  race ;  that 
it  is  not  in  one  special  direction  nor  under  one  specific 
term  that  this  treasure  can  be  cultivated,  but  that 
individuals  and  peoples  in  their  combined  international 
life  exhibit  and  perpetuate  it. 

A  number  of  words  have  during  this  century  been  in-        is. 

Different 

troduced  by  various  systems  of  philosophy  to  denote  this  terms  for 

*     *  expressing 

unity  of  the  inner  life  of  mankind  :  Hegel's  Geist,  Comte's  tbis  unity< 
Humanity,  Lotze's  Microcosm,  Spencer's  Social  Organism, 
all  refer  to  special  sides  and  aspects  of  thje  same  subject. 
And  it  is  interesting  to  note  how_  the  greatschools  of 
Idealism  in  Germany vpj  Positivism  in  France,  of  Evolu- 
tion—pTiysicaTand  mental — in  England,  and — in  spite  of 
their  apparently  disintegrating  tendencies — how  the  social 
changes  of  the  Revolution  and  the  specialisations  of  science 
have  all  combined  to  emphasise  this  unity  of  human  life 
and  interests.  To  show  this  in  detail  is  the  object  I  have 
in  view.  So  far  we  have  not  committed  ourselves  to  any 
of  the  many  existing  theories  :  the  word  Thought  seems  to  14. 

•  i  Definition  of 

me  to  be  capable  of  the  widest  application,  and  to  denote  Thought. 
in  the  most  catholic  spirit  whatever  of  truth  and  value 
may  be  contained  in  the  combined  aim  and  endeavour  of 
VOL.  i.  c 


34 


INTRODUCTION. 


all  these  modern  aspirations.     A  history  of  this  thought 
will  be  a  definition  of  Thought  itself. 

Much  has  been  done  in  the  course  of  this  century  to 

prepare  for  an  undertaking  such  as  the  one  before  me.     It 

will  be  well  to  review  shortly  this  special  side  of  modern 

literature.     We  have  indeed  passed  out  of  what  may  be 

is.        called  the  age  of  encyclopaedic  treatment  of  learning — the 

1750  to  1850. 

The  age  of    hundred  years  from  the  middle  of  the  last  to  the  middle 

encyclopse-  * 

mentor1"  °^  ^ne  present  century.1  The  plan  of  such  an  arrangement 
ing'  of  knowledge  belongs  to  an  earlier  period,  the  period  im- 
mediately succeeding  the  birth  of  modern  science.  Lord 
Bacon  was  the  father  of  it,  but  neither  he  nor  the  most 
encyclopaedic  intellect  of  modern  times,  Leibniz,  did  much 
to  realise  the  idea,  and  it  was  reserved  for  the  genius  and 
the  labours  of  Diderot  and  d'Alembert 2  in  France,  in  the 


1  "  Encyclopaedia  nomen  hodie 
frequentius  auditur  quam  alias." — 
Gessner  in  Gottinger  Lections-Kata- 
log  for  1756. 

a  Diderot's  "  Prospectus  "  to  the 
'  Encyclopedic '  appeared  1750  ;  the 
first  volume  appeared  1751  with  the 
celebrated  "  Discours  preliminaire  " 
of  d'Alembert  and  a  reprint  of  the 
"  Prospectus."  The  complete  title 
was  '  Encyclopedic  ou  dictionnaire 
raisonne"  des  sciences,  des  arts  et 
me"tier3,  par  une  soci^te"  de  gens  de 
lettres,  mis  en  ordre  et  public"  par 
Diderot  et  d'Alembert.'  The  prin- 
ciples which  guided  the  editors, 
and  the  object  of  the  work,  are  ex- 
plained, with  repeated  references  to 
Lord  Bacon,  in  this  introduction, 
as  well  as  in  the  article  "Encyclo- 
pedic," in  the  fifth  volume  (1755), 
which  was  written  by  Diderot,  and 
occupied  28  pages.  See  also  Did- 
erot's '  Peuse"es  sur  1'interpretation 
de  la  Nature,'  published  anony- 
mously in  1754. 


Copious  details  about  the  history, 
the  reception,  and  the  influence  of 
the  '  Encyclopedic '  are  to  be  found 
in  the  correspondence  and  memoirs 
of  Grimm,  d'Alembert,  and  Vol- 
taire, Madame  d'Epinay,  the  Abbe 
Morellet,  and  many  others.  They 
are  combined  into  a  concise  narra- 
tive, giving  all  the  important  facts, 
in  Roseukranz's  '  Leben  und  Werke 
Diderots,'  2  vols.,  Leipzig,  1866, 
and  in  John  Morley's  '  Diderot.' 

It  is  interesting  to  note  how  the 
•idea  of  the  unifying  and  life-giving 
influence  of  thought  was  as  familiar 
to  Diderot  as  it  is  to  us  :  "  Si  Ton 
bannit  1'homme  ou  I'etre  pensant 
et  contemplateur  de  dessus  la  sur- 
face de  la  terre  ;  ce  spectacle  pathe- 
tique  et  sublime  de  la  nature  ii'est 
plus  qu'une  scene  triste  et  muette. 
L'univers  se  tait ;  le  silence  et  la 
nuit  s'en  emparent.  Tout  se  change 
en  une  vaste  solitude,  ou  les  pheno- 
menes  inobserves  se  passent  d'une 
maniere  obscure  et  sourde.  .  .  . 


INTRODUCTION. 


35 


middle  of  the  eighteenth  century,  to  carry  out  the  plan, 
foreshadowed  in  the  '  Novum  Organum,'  of  collecting  all 
knowledge,  which  had  been  accumulated  ever  since  science 
had  been  liberated  from  the  fetters  of  theology,  into  one 
comprehensive  whole.  It  must,  however,  be  admitted 
that  whilst  the  practical  end  of  these  laborious  under- 
takings, the  diffusion  of  knowledge,  has  certainly  been 
greatly  furthered,  the  original  idea,  that  the  sum  of 
human  knowledge  is  an  organic  whole,  has  in  the  exe- 
cution  been  by  degrees  entirely  lost  sight  of.  The  unity 
of  thought  and  knowledge  was  indeed  referred  to  in 
Diderot's  "  Prospectus  "  and  d'Alembert's  "  Discours  pre- 
liminaire,"  and  in  the  introduction  to  Ersch  and  Gruber's 
great  Encyclopaedia,1  as  also  in  Coleridge's  celebrated  essay 


i«. 

knowledge 

gradually 


Voila  ce  qui  nous  a  determine  h, 
chercher  dans  les  facultesprincipales 
•de  1'homme  la  division  ge"nerale  a 
laquelle  nous  avons  subordonne" 
notre  travail." — Article  "Encyclo- 
pedic,5 p.  641. 

1  Ersch  und  Gruber's 'Allgemeine 
Encyclopiidie  der  Wissenschaften 
und  Kiinste,'  Leipzig,  1818  to  1875, 
unfinished,  151  vols.  It  was  founded 
by  Professor  Johann  Samuel  Ersch, 
librarian  at  Halle  in  1813,  assisted 
by  Hufeland,  Gruber,  Meier,  and 
Brockhaus,  and  contained  contri- 
butions by  the  most  learned  and 
«minent  Germans  of  the  century. 
It  is  interesting  to  compare  the 
plan  and  principles  which  guided 
the  editors,  as  expounded  in  the  in- 
troductions to  the  first  and  second 
volumes,  with  the  corresponding 
dissertations  prefixed  to  the  '  Ency- 
clopedic '  in  France  and  the  '  Ency- 
clopaedia Metropolitana'  in  England. 
The  unity  aimed  at  by  Bacon  was 
either  purely  formal,  securing  only 
•uniformity  and  completeness  of 
ireatmen.t,  or  it  was  that  of  prac- 


tical usefulness — the  philosophy  of 
fruit  and  progress.  The  plan  adopt- 
ed by  Diderot  and  d'Alembert  could 
hardly  attain  anything  more  than 
this.  Coleridge,  nursed  in  German 
philosophy,  and  deeply  impressed 
with  the  fact  that  there  is  a  higher 
view  than  that  of  Lord  Bacon,  and 
that  such  is  to  be  found  rather  in 
writers  like  Plato  and  Shakespeare, 
uses  the  word  method  in  a  much 
wider  sense.  He  was  deeply  affect- 
ed by  the  spirit  of  the  idealistic 
philosophy,  which  was  foreign  to 
Bacon  and  unduly  despised  by  him. 
In  the  idealistic  systems  of  the 
Continent,  beginning  with  Kant, 
the  opinion  was  current  that  the 
methods  and  treatment  of  science 
alone  were  insufficient  to  close  the 
circle  of  knowledge.  The  truly 
encyclopaedic  view  was  only  possible 
in  a  scientific  investigation  speci- 
ally carried  on  for  that  purpose, 
and  this  was  considered  to  be  one 
of  the  main  objects  of  philosophy. 
Thus  Kant  in  many  passages  of  his 
works,  notably  vol.  ii.  pp.  377,  378, 


36 


INTRODUCTION. 


on  the  science  of  method  prefixed  to  the  '  Encyclopaedia 
Metropolitana ' ;  but  the  result  has  shown,  what  was  not 
evident  to  Lord  Bacon,  that  neither  a  systematic  division 
of  learning  according  to  some  logical  principle,  nor  the  his- 
torical identity  of  the  beginnings  of  all  branches  of  know- 
ledge, can  in  the  end  preserve  the  real  unity  and  integrity 
of  thought.  The  work  of  the  advancement  of  learning, 
if  it  be  once  handed  over  to  different  sciences  and  in- 
trusted to  separate  labourers,  does  not  proceed  in  a  cycle 
which  runs  back  into  itself,  but  rather  in  the  rings  of  an 
ever-increasing  spiral,  receding  more  and  more  from  the 
common  origin.  Such  is  the  impression  we  get  if  we 
contemplate  the  unfinished 1  rows  of  Ersch  and  Gruber's 


613  ;  vol.  iii.  pp.  188,  212  ;  vol.  v. 
p.  312  (Rosenkrauz's  edition),  especi- 
ally the  two  following  :  "  Philos- 
ophy is  the  only  science  which  can 
procure  for  us  inner  satisfaction, 
for  she  closes  the  scientific  cycle, 
and  through  her  only  do  the  scien- 
ces receive  order  and  connection." 
And  :  "  Mere  '  iroXviffropla. '  is  a 
cyclopeau  learning  which  wants  one 
eye — the  eye  of  Philosophy — and 
a  cyclops  among  mathematicians, 
historians,  naturalists,  philologists, 
and  linguists,  is  a  scholar  who  is 
great  in  all  these  lines,  but  having 
these  considers  all  philosophy  as 
superfluous."  Still,  with  Kant 
Philosophy  is  not  an  "instrument 
for  the  extension,"  but  merely  a 
study  of  "the  limits  of  knowledge"  ; 
she  does  not  "discover  truth," 
but  only  "prevents  error."  This 
modest  definition  was  given  up  in 
the  systems  of  Fichte,  Schelling, 
and  Hegel,  who  maintained  that  a 
certain  kind  of — and  this  the  highest 
— knowledge  could  be  attained  by 
starting  from  one  highest  principle 
deductively  :  the  all  -  embracing, 
encyclopaedic  character  of  philoso- 


phical, speculative  knowledge  was 
increasingly  emphasised,  and  this- 
not  only  in  special  lectures  on  the 
subject,  as  in  Fichte's  lectures  on, 
"The  Nature  of  the  Scholar,"  in 
Schelling's  on  "The  Method  of 
Academic  Study,"  in  Hegel's  'Ency- 
clopaedia of  Philosophy,'  but  also 
in  the  regeneration  and  reform  of 
many  older  and  in  the  foundation* 
of  new  universities  and  academies 
throughout  Germany.  The  great 
'  Encyclopaedia'  of  Ersch  and  Gruber 
was  planned  in  a  similar  spirit,  as 
the  reform  of  university  teaching 
and  of  academic  learning.  This 
reform  has  been  of  the  greatest  im- 
portance to  the  German  nation  and 
to  the  interests  of  science  and 
knowledge.  The  Encyclopaedia,  on 
the  other  hand,  has  remained 
incomplete,  a  huge  but  abortive 
attempt  to  combine  not  only  the- 
principles  of  knowledge,  but  also 
the  colossal  and  growing  volume  of 
it,  into  a  systematic  whole. 

1  The  promoters  of  it  were  evi- 
dently not  sufficiently  impressed 
with  the  two  very  essential  con- 
ditions which  make  a  work  of  this- 


INTRODUCTION. 


37 


volumes,  or  if  we  recognise  the  fact  that  the  more  useful 
and  popular  publications  of  our  day  have  abandoned  the 
philosophical  introductions  and  preliminary  discourses1 
by  which  the  earlier  works  preserved  a  semblance  of 
unity  and  method,  and  are  contented  to  be  merely  useful 
dictionaries  of  reference.  The  encyclopaedic  treatment  of 
knowledge,  the  execution  of  Lord  Bacon's  scheme,  has 
shown  that  the  extension  and  application  of  learning 
leads  to  the  disintegration,  not  to  the  unification,  of 
knowledge  and  thought.  A  conviction  of  this  sort  is  17. 

.  Lectures  on 

no  doubt  the  reason  why  in  German  universities  lectures  "  Bncycio- 

padie  " 

on  "  Encyclopadie  "  have  been  abandoned.2     They  were  f^^n 
very  general   and   popular  in   the  earlier  years  of  the  umverslties- 
century,  when,  under  the  influence  of  Kant,  Fichte,  and 


kind  useful — viz.,  that  it  must  be 
finished,  however  imperfect  it  may 
be,  and  that  it  must  be  completed 
within  a  limited  time,  on  account  of 
the  revolutions  and  smaller  changes 
in  thought  and  knowledge.  These 
essential  conditions  were  always  be- 
fore the  mind  of  Diderot.  See  his 
article  "Encyclopedic,"  pp.  636-644. 
1  The  object  of  the  philosophical 
introductions  has  in  course  of  this 
•century  been  much  more  completely 
.attained  by  such  works  as  Mill's 
'  Logic '  and  Jevons's  '  Principles  of 
Science';  whilst  the  "preliminary 
dissertations,"  such  as  were  con- 
tained in  the  older  editions  of  the 
'  Encyclopaedia  Britannica,'  have 
been  partially  superseded  by  works 
like  Whewell's  '  History '  and  his 
'  Philosophy  of  the  Inductive  Sci- 
ences,' in  which  the  common  origin, 
the  genesis,  the  continuous  develop- 
ment and  interdependence  of  the 
different  sciences,  are  traced.  The 
value  in  this  respect  of  an  under- 
taking like  that  of  the  Royal  Ba- 


varian Academy  ('Geschichte  der 
Wissenschaften  in  Deutschland,' 
vol.  L,  1864  :  it  has  now  reached 
22  vols.,  the  science  of  War  signifi- 
cantly filling  three  large  volumes, 
that  of  Mathematics  one  small  one) 
is  much  diminished  by  the  title 
suggesting  that  science  is  a  nation- 
al, not  a  cosmopolitan  or  interna- 
tional concern.  Fortunately  many 
of  the  contributors  to  this  impor- 
tant and  highly  useful  publication 
have  not  limited  their  narratives 
to  purely  German  science,  but  have 
largely  taken  notice  of  non-German 
research.  Special  reports  on  the 
state  of  any  science  or  branch  of 
science  in  a  nation  have,  of  course, 
quite  a  different  meaning  and 
value. 

2  The  term  is  still  in  use  for 
courses  of  lectures  giving  a  gen- 
eral and  comprehensive  view  of 
special  sciences  :  thus,  "  Encyclopa- 
die des  Rechts,  der  Medicin,  der 
Philologie,  der  Philosophic,  der 
Theologie." 


38 


INTRODUCTION. 


Schleiermacher,  university  teaching  and  learning  entered 
on  a  new  era,  in  which  the  idea  prevailed  that  com- 
pleteness, universality,  and  unity  of  knowledge  could  be 
secured  by  one  and  the  same  arrangement  of  study.1  It 
was  the  age  when  philosophy  for  the  last  time  had  got  a 
firm  hold  of  all  departments  of  knowledge,  and  permeated 
all  scientific  pursuits ; 2  when,  favoured  by  political  events, 


1  On  this  subject  the  literature 
connected  with  the  foundation  of 
the  University  of  Berlin  in  the  year 
1809  is  of  special  interest.  It  was 
essentially  the  creation  of  Wilhelm 
von  Humboldt,  though  prepared  by 
Wolf  and  Beyme  in  1807.  See 
Seeley,  '  Life  of  Stein,'  vol.  ii.  p. 
430  «/<?.  ;  Haym,  '  Leben  W.  v. 
Humboldts,'  p.  270  sqq.  The  foun- 
dation of  this  university  in  the  year 
of  Prussia's  greatest  misery,  when 
the  first  gleams  of  liberty  in  the 
rising  of  Spain  and  the  success  of 
Aspern  had  been  extinguished  by 
the  defeat  of  Wagram,  the  voting 
of  £22,500  per  annum  for  the  pur- 
poses of  the  new  University  and 
the  Academy  of  Science  and  Arts, 
when  a  crushing  war-tax  hung  over 
the  country,  when  land  was  depre- 
ciated, the  necessaries  of  life  at 
famine  prices,  the  currency  of  the 
country  at  a  large  discount,  when 
every  one,  from  the  king  to  the 
lowest  subject,  was  forced  into  sac- 
rifices and  economies  of  every  kind, 
was  an  act  as  heroic  as  the  great 
deeds  on  the  battle-field,  and  as  far- 
seeing  as  the  measures  of  Stein  and 
Scharnhorst.  Interesting  from  our 
point  of  view  are  the  ideas  of  Fichte 
on  university  teaching  and  academic 
learning,  laid  down  in  his  '  Dedu- 
cirter  Plan  einer  zu  Berlin  zu  errich- 
tenden  hbheren  Lehranstalt,'  writ- 
ten at  the  request  of  the  minister 
Beyme  in  1807.  In  it  a  great  deal 
is  said  about  encyclopaedic  treat- 
ment. The  question  of  the  position 


of  philosophy  in  the  encyclopaedic 
or  academic  treatment  of  knowledge 
was  easily  solved  in  the  Kantian 
school,  to  which  most  of  the  above- 
mentioned  writers  belonged.  Later 
on  in  the  school  of  Schelliug  it  be- 
came more  difficult.  It  was  fre- 
quently discussed  by  Schelling  him- 
self, who  was  one  of  those  that 
initiated  the  new  era  in  the  Academy 
of  Munich,  which  was  remodelled 
in  the  year  1807.  See,  inttr  alia, 
Schilling's  essay,  "  Suggestions  con- 
cerning the  Occupation  of  the  Philo- 
logico- Philosophical  Class"  of  the 
Academy,  and  especially  the  follow  - 
ingremarkablepassageC  Werke.:  vol. 
viii.p.  464  ):  "  If,  indeed, Philosophy 
were  denied  living  contact  with  real 
things,  if  she  were  obliged  to  soar 
in  transcendent  regions  without  end 
and  measure,  and  to  rise  a  hungry 
guest  from  the  well-appointed  table 
of  Nature  and  Art,  of  History  and 
Life  :  then  it  would  be  incompre- 
hensible how  she  could  still  find  so- 
much  support  as  to  be  received  in 
an  academy,  and  it  would  be  much 
better  if  we  also  followed  the  path 
of  other  nations,  who  have  lately 
said  good-bye  to  all  philosophy,  and 
have  thrown  themselves,  with  the 
most  glowing  ardour,  upon  the  ex- 
ploration of  Nature  and  Reality  in 
every  direction." 

-  The  principal  representatives  of 
the  encyclopaedic  teaching  at  the 
German  universities  were  Eschen- 
burg,  Krug.  and  Gruber.  The 
latter,  in  his  introduction  to  the 


INTRODUCTION. 


39 


18. 

Encyclo- 


ideal  aims,  a  generous  spirit  of  self-sacrifice,  and  a  feeling 
of  one  common  duty  pervaded  the  German  nation,  and 
foremost  in  it  the  teachers  and  students  of  the  German 
universities.1     This   spirit,   as   it   produced   co-operation 
and  unity  of  action,  also  favoured  unity  of  thought,  and 
contributed  much  to  the  popularity  of  several  philosoph- 
ical systems  which  promised  more  than  they  could  give.  p*dias  did 
Encyclopedic   surveys  were  then   supposed  to  be  more  *haear£dy 
than   the   empty   shell,   the   mere   skeleton  of    learning to  promise- 
which  they  have  since  proved  to  be ;  they  were  looked 
upon  as  being  able  to  grasp  and  convey  the  living  spirit 
of    knowledge.     This   phase   of    thought,  which   in   the 
sequel   will    largely   command    our    attention,   has    dis- 


second  volume  of  Ersch  and  Gruber's 
'  Encyclopadie,'  gives  a  definition 
and  history  of  encyclopedic  study, 
which,  according  to  him,  was  intro- 
duced into  the  modern  (German) 
universities  together  with  the  philo- 
sophical faculty.  In  the  beginning 
this  was  subservient  to  the  three 
higher  faculties  (theology,  law,  and 
medicine),  but  gradually  took  the 
lead.  He  argues  that  only  since 
university  studies  have  become  en- 
cyclopaedic can  they  be  considered 
as  furthering  true  humanity.  He 
refers  to  the  great  crisis  through 
which  in  the  beginning  of  the  cen- 
tury literature,  science,  and  arts 
were  passing  (p.  li),  and  mentions 
the  conflicting  principles  in  the 
treatment  of  mathematics,  physics, 
history,  philosophy,  and  philology. 
See  also  the  '  Vorbericht,'  vol.  i. 
p.  vii. 

1  Among  the  mass  of  literature 
dealing  with  this  subject,  the 
'  Memoirs  of  Frederick  Perthes, ' 
by  his  son  (English  translation, 
•vol.  i.  chap.  xi.  sqq.),  and  Steftens's 
'  Autobiography '  ('  Was  ich  erlebte,' 


Breslau,  1840-44,  10  vols.),  give  the 
most  vivid  and  exhaustive  accounts. 
Neither  Stein,  the  great  statesman, 
nor  Goethe,  the  great  poet  and 
thinker  of  the  age,  took  part  in  this 
alliance  of  the  patriotic  and  intellec- 
tual interests  of  the  German  nation. 
Stein's  attitude  to  the  idealism  of 
the  age  is  defined  by  Seeley,  '  Life 
of  Stein  '  (vol.  i.  p.  30,  "  It  is  desir- 
able to  mark  that  between  him 
and  the  literature  and  philosophy 
of  his  time  and  country  there  was 
no  connection  at  all "),  and  is  ex- 
pressed in  a  remarkable  conversa- 
tion which  he  had  with  Steffens, 
March  1813,  at  Breslau  (quoted  by 
Seeley,  vol.  iii.  p.  119  ;  Steffens,  vol. 
vii.  p.  120  sqq. )  Goethe's  position  is 
denned  by  his  reply  to  the  invitation 
to  contribute  to  the  '  Deutsches 
Museum,1  a  periodical  planned  by 
the  bookseller  Perthes.  It  was  to 
be  a  scientific  alliance  of  all  the  in- 
tellect of  Germanjr,  and  was  in  time 
"  to  be  transformed  into  a  polit- 
ical one  possessing  the  strength  and 
union  necessary  for  vigorous  action  " 
(Perthes'  Memoirs,  vol.  i.  p.  167). 


40 


INTRODUCTION. 


appeared;  the  second  half  of  our  century  does  not 
expect  to  find  the  essence  of  knowledge  condensed  in 
any  philosophical  formula,  any  more  than  it  expects  to 
find  the  real  unity  and  integrity  of  thought  preserved  in 
the  fragmentary  articles  of  an  alphabetical  dictionary. 
The  purpose  of  the  latter  is  purely  practical;  it  is  a 
popular  and  handy  instrument  for  the  diffusion  of 
knowledge,  whilst  philosophical  divisions  are  merely 
formal,  and  at  best  are  applicable  only  to  a  narrow 
and  limited  sphere  of  research.1 

The  age  of  encyclopaedic  representation  of  learning 
and  the  short  period  of  philosophical  formalism  seem 
both  to  belong  to  the  past;  but  the  desire  of  bringing 
together  what  is  scattered,  of  focussing  knowledge  and 
learning,  and  of  realising  the  organic  continuity  and  unity 
of  thought  and  progress,  is  as  great  as,  perhaps  greater 
than  ever.  Neither  the  shapelessness  of  a  huge  dictionary 
nor  the  barrenness  of  a  concise  formula  will  satisfy  the 


1  It  is  interesting  to  observe  the 
development  and  spread  of  encyclo- 
paedic learning  in  the  three  coun- 
tries. Encyclopaedias  in  the  modern 
sense  have  their  origin,  like  so  many 
other  modern  institutions  and  ideas, 
in  England.  They  were  there  com- 
piled mainly  for  practical  purposes. 
France  took  up  the  scheme  in  a 
philosophical  spirit,  and  carried  it 
as  far  as  it  is  capable  of  being 
carried  under  this  aspect.  At- 
tempts to  improve  and  amplify 
the  plan  proved  impracticable ;  and 
when  subjected  to  the  vast  eru- 
dition of  Germany,  it  became  evi- 
dent that  unity,  depth,  and  breadth 
of  view  could  not  be  maintained. 
In  course  of  this  century  the  coun- 
try which  produced  the  classical  era 


of  encycloptedism  has  done  least  for 
encyclopaedic  learning.  This  has 
now  its  home  in  Germany,  where 
encyclopaedic  labours  have  been 
specialised,  and  where  every  science 
is  represented  by  some  compilation 
or  annual  register  aiming  at  collect- 
ing and  systematically  arranging  the 
scattered  contributions  of  the  whole 
world.  But  it  would  be  ungrateful 
not  to  mention  the  Royal  Society's 
catalogue  of  scientific  papers,  and 
the  services  which  America  has  ren- 
dered in  summarising  the  literary 
productions  of  the  English-speaking 
nations  in  such  works  as  Poole's 
'Index  to  Periodical  Literature.' 
Without  the  aid  of  such  laborious 
compilations  the  present  work  could 
not  have  been  undertaken. 


INTRODUCTION. 


41 


deeper  conviction  that  all  mental  work  is  living,  indi- 
vidual, and  of  endless  variety.  To  stimulate  individual 
thought,  to  bring  about  life  and  change,  is  nowadays  felt 
to  be  quite  as  necessary  as  to  insist  on  method,  system, 
and  order.  Prompted  by  this  conviction,  the  last  fifty 
years  have  done  much  to  facilitate  intellectual  inter- 
change, and  to  record  the  historical  development  of  all 
branches  of  science. 

This  object  has  been  promoted  in  three  different  ways. 
The  French,  who  in  the  beginning  of  the  period  were  the       19. 

French  were 

masters  in  science,  led  the  way  by  founding  a  series  of  the  masters 

in  science 

periodicals  devoted  to  the  development  of  separate  sciences,  ^irfning 
Germany  followed,  and  still  later   England.1     A  living  g^ 


1  The  oldest  scientific  periodical 
is  the  '  Journal  des  Savants,'  which 
was  started  in  1665  in  Paris;  next 
to  it  comes  probably  Rozier's  '  Ob- 
servations sur  la  Physique'  (1771), 
continued  under  the  title  '  Journal 
de  Physique'  (1778,  continued  with 
interruptions  from  1794  -  95  till 
1823).  In  opposition  to  this 
journal,  which  defended  the  older 
phlogistic  theories  in  chemistry, 
the  '  Annales  de  Chimie  '  were 
started  in  1789  by  Berthollet, 
Guyton  de  Morveau,  and  Fourcroy, 
as  an  organ  of  Lavoisier's  ideas. 
In  1788  the  Societe  Philomatique 
started  its  '  Bulletin,'  and  in  1795 
the  '  Journal  de  1'Ecole  Poly- 
technique  '  started  its  influential 
career.  No  such  periodicals  existed 
for  special  sciences  at  that  time  in 
any  other  country,  if  we  perhaps 
except  the  '  Transactions  of  the 
Royal  Linnsean  Society,'  which 
started  in  1791.  '  Nicholson's 
Journal '  started  in  1797  ;  the 
'  London,  Edinburgh,  and  Dublin 
Philosophical  Magazine  and  Journal 
of  Sciences '  had  its  origin  in  Til- 
loch's  '  Philosophical  Magazine' ;  but 


the  first  journal  devoted  specially 
to  mathematical  sciences  in  England 
was  probably  the  '  Cambridge  Ma- 
thematical Journal,'  started  in  1839. 
In  the  meantime  the  number  of 
scientific  journals  in  France  had 
grown  enormously.  In  Germany  we 
have  Crell's  '  Chemische  Annalen ' 
(1778),  Gehlen's  'Allgemeines  Jour- 
nal fiir  Chemie'  (1803),  Gren's 
'Journal  der  Physik'  (1790),  Gil- 
bert's '  Annaleu  der  Physik'  (1799), 
Zach's  '  Monatliche  Correspondenz ' 
(1800),  Crelle's  'Journal  fiir  die 
reine  und  angewandte  Mathematik' 
(1826),  and  many  others,  all  peri- 
odicals of  the  first  imoortance.  The 
'  Transactions  of  the  Royal  Society,' 
which  of  course  contain  many  of 
the  valuable  scientific  contributions 
of  this  country,  can  nevertheless 
hardly  be  looked  upon  as  a  reposi- 
tory of  the  work  of  English  mathe- 
maticians and  physicists  of  the 
period  in  question, — not  even  as 
much  as  the  Memoirs  of  the  Paris 
Academy  in  France.  In  Great 
Britain  a  new  centre  of  scientific 
and  literary  work  existed  during 
the  latter  part  of  the  last  century 


42 


INTRODUCTION. 


intercourse  between  men  of  science  was  greatly  promoted 
by  the  British  Association  for  the  Advancement  of  Science, 
which  held  its  first  meeting  at  York  in  1831.  Associa- 
tions and  meetings  of  this  kind  had  their  origin  ten  years 
earlier  in  Germany  through  Oken  ; l  but  the  line  in  which 
Germany  has  done  most  is  the  establishing  of  and  con- 
tinuing annual  Reports 2  of  the  progress  of  the  different 


in  Edinburgh  ( '  Transactions  of  the 
Royal  Society  of  Edinburgh,'  started 
in  1788),  and  somewhat  later  like- 
wise in  Dublin  ('  Transactions  of  the 
Royal  Society  of  Dublin,'  started 
1799),  and  Manchester  ('Memoirs 
of  the  Manchester  Philosophical 
Society,'  started  in  1789).  Many 
of  the  first  scientific  writers  of  the 
age  published  in  these  provincial 
papers  or  in  separate  pamphlets — 
the  want  of  a  common  collecting 
centre  being  very  obvious. 

1  Alexander   v.    Humboldt    sup- 
ported them,  and  was  instrumental 
in  giving  to  the  Assembly  at  Berlin 
in  1828— which  he  called  "The  in- 
vasion of  philosophers  " — a  special 
importance.     It    was,    as    he    says, 
"  a  noble  manifestation  of  scientific 
union  in  Germany ;  it  presents  the 
spectacle   of    a    nation    divided  in 
politics  and  religion,  revealing  its 
nationality  in  the  realm  of  intellec- 
tual  progress." — Bruhns,   'Life  of 
A.   v.   Humboldt,'  vol.    ii.  p.  130. 
The  British  Association  for  the  Ad- 
vancement of  Science  was  (as  Prof. 
Owen    informs    us)   at   the    outset 
avowedly  organised  after  the  Oken- 
ian  model. — '  Encyclopedia  Britan- 
nica,'  art.  "Oken." 

2  The    first    reports    aiming    at 
giving  a  statement  of  the  position 
of  Science  were  those  drawn  up  by 
Delambre  and  Cuvier  at  the  request 
of  the  Emperor  Napoleon  I.,  and 
presented  in  the  year  1808  under 
the  title  '  Discours  sur  les  Progres 
des  Sciences,  Lettres,  et  Arts  depuis 


1789  jusqu'a  ce  jour '  (1808).  They 
were  imitated  on  a  larger  scale  by 
the  Emperor  Napoleon  III.,  on  the 
occasion  of  the  great  Paris  Exhibi- 
tion 1867,  and  have  been  continued 
under  the  Republic.  Of  the  report 
of  1808  Cuvier  says,  "Ce  tableau 
historique  nous  servira  desormais 
de  point  de  depart  et  nos  rapports 
annuels  en  seront  autant  de  con- 
tinuations." He  also  adds  signifi- 
cantly, "  Dans  les  relations  actives 
ou  nous  nous  trouvons  avec  la 
plupart  de  ceux  qui  cultivent  les 
sciences,  il  est  bien  difficile  qu'ils  se 
f assent  en  Europe  quelques  decou- 
vertes  importantes  sans  que  le 
bruit  en  retentisse  promptement 
dans  cette  enceinte,  et  nous  excite 
a  des  travaux  qui  s'y  rapportent 
plus  ou  moins  directement. " 

By  far  the  most  important  work 
of  reporting  and  summarising  the 
results  of  scientific  labour  has  been 
done  by  Germany.  The  first  publi- 
cation of  this  kind,  however,  origin- 
ated with  Berzelius,  who  from  the 
year  1821  reported  regularly  to  the 
Academy  of  Stockholm  on  the  pro- 
gress of  the  physical  sciences.  Of 
Berzelius's  periodical  Kopp  says 
('Geschichte  der  Chemie,'  vol.  i.  p. 
403),  that  it  "  summarises  with  the 
greatest  completeness  all  that  had 
been  done  in  chemistry  since  1820." 
This  work,  which  regularly  ap- 
peared in  German  translation,  was 
continued  in  Liebig's  '  Jahresbericht 
der  Chemie' (1847).  In  Berlin  the 
'  Physikalische  Gesellschaft '  has 


INTRODUCTION.  43 

sciences,  in  which  all  scientific  researches  are — without 
regard  to  nationality — reviewed,  classified,  and  arranged  in 
the  most  complete  manner,  according  to  the  place  which 
they  occupy  in  the  general  development.  Invaluable  ser- 
vice has  also  been  done  in  England  by  special  Eeports  or 
Addresses,  prepared  by  men  of  the  greatest  eminence — fre- 
quently at  the  request  of  the  British  Association — in  which 
the  position  of  special  branches  of  science  is  explained,  the 
work  of  the  past  summed  up,  the  leading  principles  clearly 
brought  out,  and  the  unsolved  problems  placed  promi- 
nently before  the  minds  of  young  and  aspiring  workers. 

In  Germany  during  the  first  half  of  the  century  a        20. 

Reaction 

reaction  set  in   against   the   metaphysical   treatment   of  in  Germany 

against  me- 

scientific  subjects,  which  had   been   exaggerated  in  the  ^t^^ft 
schools  of  Schelling  and  Hegel.     Experimental  research,  subjects.180 
following  mainly  the  great  French  and  English  models, 
was   next  favoured,  and   through   the   establishment   of 
laboratories  and  observatories,  through  voyages  of   dis- 
covery and  the  application  of  science  to  the  industries, 
an  enormous  amount  of  detailed  and  minute  knowledge 
was  accumulated.1     For  a  time — even  within  the  limits 


the  Cavendish  Society,  1848),  and 
the  '  Handworterbuch  der  reinen 
und  angewandten  Chemie '  (edited 
by  Liebig  jointly  with  Poggendorf 
and  Wohler,  1837).  The  same  age 
also  set  going  and  filled  the  volumes 
of  Liebig's  '  Annalen  '  (started  by 
Hiinle  in  1823  under  the  title 
'Magazin  der  Pharmacie,'  it  finally 
assumed  the  title  of  'Annalen  der 
Chemie  und  Pharmacie '  under  Lie- 

the   great  repositories  of  chemical   !   big's    editorship),    of    Poggendorf 's 
knowledge.      Such    were    Gmelin's       '  Annalen  der  Physik  und  Chemie ' 


continued  to  issue  regularly  since 
1845  annual  Reports  under  the  title 
'  Fortschritte  der  Physik.'  But  it 
was  only  in  1868  that  a  similar 
annual  was  started  in  Berlin  having 
reference  to  mathematics,  under 
the  title  'Fortschritte  der  Mathe- 
matik.'  A  '  Jahresbericht '  on 
Zoology  has  appeared  ever  since 
1879,  and  one  on  Botany  since  1873. 
It  was  the  age  which  compiled 


:  Handbuch  der  Chemie'  (1st  ed., 
1817.     Translated  into  English  by 


(1824),  and  the  '  Annales  de  Chimie 
et  de  Physique.' 


44  INTRODUCTION. 

of  exact  reasoning — attempts  to  condense  and  unify 
knowledge  were  discredited.  The  result — especially  in 
Germany — was  that  in  many  sciences  information  be- 
came buried  in  periodicals  ami  in  the  memoirs  of  learned 
societies:  text -books  were  chiefly  written  by  men  of 
secondary  importance,  translated  from  the  French  and 
English,  and  frequently  on  somewhat  antiquated  lines.1 
The  new  spirit  which  began  to  leaven  scientific  research  in 
the  middle  of  the  century  was  confined  to  a  few  master 
minds,  who — frequently  almost  unknown — marched  in 
advance  of  their  age.  In  the  course  of  the  last  thirty 
years  this  has  been  entirely  changed.  The  means  of 
intercourse  and  communication,  referred  to  above,  make 
scientific  isolation  almost  impossible ;  the  necessity  has 
21.  been  felt  of  remodelling  the  whole  of  the  popular  school 

Reform  in 

school  liters-  literature  on  more  modern  lines :  some  of  the  first  in- 

tnie. 

1  The  greater  part  of  the  higher  portant  work  of  this  kind.  Ger- 
Gennau  school  literature  in  mathe-  many  had  indeed  not  been  wanting 
matics  and  physics  was  supplied  by  in  original  research,  but  the  new 
the  French  or  modelled  on  French  ideas  of  Mubius,  Steiner,  Staudt, 
ideas — Legendre  and  Monge  in  ele-  Pliicker,  and  Grassmann  in  geom- 
mentary  and  descriptive  geometry,  etry  found  no  adherents  till,  mainly 
Lacrois  in  the  higher  branches.  through  the  translation  of  Sal- 
Francreur's  course  of  mathematics  mon's  text-books  by  Fiedler,  a  new 
was  introduced  in  England  as  well  spirit  came  over  geometrical  teach- 
as  Germany ;  Poisson,  and  later  ing.  In  the  meantime  Lejeune 
Lagrange  and  Dubamel,  became  Dirichlet.  and  Neumann  the  elder, 
the  models  in  mechanics,  Biot  and  cultivated  in  their  academical  lec- 
Pouillet  in  experimental  physics,  tures  the  higher  branches  of  mathe- 
Regnault  in  chemistry.  The  only  matical  physics,  and  educated  a 
great  popular  authorities  which  whole  generation  of  mathematicians 
did  not  belong  to  France  were  and  physicists.  Through  them  the 
Berzelius  and  Graham  in  chem-  original  researches  of  Gauss  and 
istry.  and  Euler  in  mathematics.  Jacobi  became  better  known,  and 
As  late  as  1860  hardly  any  text-  an  independent  school  of  German 
book  existed  in  Germany  on  the  mathematical  thought  was  estab- 
theoretical  and  mathematical  por-  lished.  In  England  the  influence 
tions  of  physics.  The  second  of  French  science  was  much  more 
volume  of  '  Baumgartner :  was  limited,  and  to  the  present  day 
a  miserable  compilation.  Beer's  Euclid  is  preferred  to  Legendre?s 
'  Hohere  Optik '  was  the  first  im-  more  elegant  methods. 


INTRODUCTION. 


45 


tellects  in  science  have  condescended  to  write  text-books 
of  their  subjects,  by  which  a  great  reform  has  been  brought 
about  in  the  higher  scientific  literature.1  At  the  same  time 
— after  fifty  years  of  experimental  research  and  accumula- 
tion of  material — it  has  become  necessary  to  review  the 
fundamental  principles  on  which  scientific  reasoning  rests  :  22. 

Scientific 

a  more  philosophical,  not  to  say  metaphysical,  spirit  is  reasoning 
manifesting  itself  within  the  limits  of  science.2     In  the  8°PhicaL 
abstract,  arid  especially  the  mathematical,  sciences,  real 
progress   depends    now   mainly   upon    the    discovery   of 
methods   of   simplification,  on  conciseness  and   elegance 
of  treatment,  and  on  the  discovery  of  unifying  principles 
and  generalising  aspects.3 


1  This  remark  refers   mainly  to 
England  and  Germany.     In  France, 
as  a  result  of  giving  lectures  at  the 
Ecole    Polytechnique,   the    Bureau 
des    Longitudes,    the    Faculte    des 
Sciences,  &c.,  the  great  mathema- 
ticians and  physicists  of  the  cen- 
tury have  frequently  worked  up  their 
researches   in   connected    treatises. 
For  such  we  are  indebted  to  Lame, 
Cauchy,  Poncelet,  and  many  others. 
But  the  two  works  which  in  Eng- 
land and  Germany  created  probably 
the  greatest  reform  in  the  teaching 
of   the  principles   of   natural  phil- 
osophy  were  Thomson   and   Tait's 
'  Natural  Philosophy '  (first  sketch, 
1863,  Isted.,  1867)  and  Kirchhoff's 
'  Vorlesungen  liber  Mechanik'  (Leip- 
zig, 1877). 

2  I  refer  principally  to  the  various 
writings    of    Helmholtz,    following 
those  of  Riemann,  and  the  many 
hints  thrown  out  in  Gauss's  pub- 
lished papers,  and  in  his  correspond- 
ence with  Schumacher.     Helmholtz 
has — of  all  purely  scientific  writers 
— paid  most  attention  to  the  meta- 
physical  foundations   of    geometry 


and  dynamics,  and  has  critically 
examined  the  earlier  theories  of 
Kant,  published  a  century  ago.  It 
is  interesting  in  this  respect  to  note 
what  Kant  is  reported  to  have  said 
to  Stagemann  in  1797  :  "  I  have 
come  with  my  writings  a  century 
too  soon  ;  after  a  hundred  years 
people  will  begin  to  understand  me 
rightly,  and  will  then  study  my 
books  anew  and  appreciate  them.'* 
(See  '  Tagebiicher,'  von  Varnhagen 
von  Ense,  Leipzig,  1861,  vol.  i.  p. 
46.)  Next  to  Helmholtz  we  are 
most  indebted  to  Emil  du  Bois- 
Reymond  and  his  brother  Paul. 
See  Emil's  'Reden'  (Leipzig,  1886- 
87,  2  vols.),  and  the  posthumous 
work  of  his  brother  :  '  Ueber  die 
Grundlagen  der  Erkenntniss  in  den 
exacten  Wissenschaften '  (Tubingen, 
1890). 

3  An  authority  on  this  subject 
says  :  ' '  Generality  of  aspects  and 
methods,  precision  and  elegance 
of  exposition,  have,  since  the  time 
of  Lagrange,  become  the  common 
property  of  those  who  claim  to 
be  scientific  mathematicians.  This 


46 


INTRODUCTION. 


23. 

<Jermany 
has  taken 
the  lead  in 
studying 
the  life  of 
thought. 


All  these  are  merely  external  signs  of  the  new  life,  in- 
dications of  progress  and  change:  the  inner  reason  and 
result,  the  altered  ways  of  thinking  which  underlie  or  are 
produced  by  these  external  changes,  will  be  the  object 
of  closer  study  hereafter ;  they  constitute  the  real  sub- 
stance of  this  work.  What  I  draw  attention  to  here, 
by  way  of  introduction,  are  merely  fingers  on  the  dial- 
plate  of  a  complicated  clock-work  :  their  motion  and  posi- 
tion are  patent  to  every  one.  Later  on  I  shall  invite  the 
reader  to  remove  the  outer  case,  and  try  with  me  to  under- 
stand the  delicate  working  parts  and  the  principle  of  the 
mechanism,  the  prime  mover  and  the  mode  of  transmission 
of  motion  within.  The  general  curiosity  that  exists  to  fol- 
low the  internal  and  hidden  workings  of  thought  is  mani- 
fested especially  in  that  country  which  in  modern  history 
has  frequently  taken  the  lead  in  philosophical  reasoning. 
It  is  manifested  by  the  huge  and  increasing  historical 
literature  of  Germany,  which  is  devoted  to  tracing  out 
the  growth  and  development  of  modern  science  and 
thought.  In  that  country  history  seems  for  the  moment 
to  have  taken  the  place  of  metaphysical  speculation. 
A  similar  transition  from  the  logical  to  the  historical  view 
can  be  traced  in  English  literature  in  the  last  century,  the 


generality  is  sometimes  exaggerated 
at  the  expense  of  simplicity  and 
usefulness,  and  then  leads  to  ab- 
struseness  and  to  the  enunciation 
of  theorems  which  have  no  special 
application ;  precision  may  degen- 
erate into  an  affected  brevity  which 
renders  a  dissertation  more  difficult 
to  read  than  to  write  ;  elegance  of 
form  has  in  our  days  almost  be- 
come the  test  of  the  value  of  a 
theorem.  Yet  in  spite  of  all  draw- 


backs these  conditions  of  efficient 
progress  are  of  the  greatest  import- 
ance, inasmuch  as  they  keep  the 
scientific  matter  within  those  limits 
which  are  intrinsically  necessary  if 
mathematical  research  is  not  to  lose 
itself  in  minutiae  or  be  drowned  in 
over  -  abundance."  —  Hankel,  '  Die 
Entwickelung  der  Mathematik  in 
den  letzten  Jahrhunderten '  (Tub- 
ingen, 1869). 


INTRODUCTION. 


47 


typical  representative  of  that  change  being  David  Hume, 
who,  starting  with  the  metaphysical  problems  involved  in 
Locke's  and  Berkeley's  writings,  was  from  them  led  on  to 
the  study  of  moral,  political,  and  economic  questions,  and 
ended  by  devoting  himself  to  the  study  of  history.1  At 
the  end  of  his  career  political  and  historical  writings 
were  as  frequent  in  English  literature  as  metaphysical 
and  theological  writings  had  been  at  the  beginning.  The 
causes  which  have  effected  the  same  transition  from  the 
metaphysical  to  the  historical  mode  of  treatment  in  Ger- 
many during  the  present  century  are  similar  to  those 
existing  in  England  in  the  last  century ;  but  the  whole 
movement  has  taken  place  on  a  larger  scale,  penetrates 
deeper  into  the  mental  life  and  work  of  the  nation,  and 
cannot  be  so  easily  studied  in  the  writings  of  any  great 
representative. 

Whilst  in  Germany  historical  studies  are  now  foremost, 


24. 

Causes  of 
transition 
from  meta- 
physical to 
historical 
method. 


1  I  am  quite  aware  that  general- 
isations of  this  kind  must  be  made 
and  used  with  great  caution.  I 
therefore  refer  my  readers  to  Les- 
lie Stephen's  '  History  of  English 
Thought  in  the  Eighteenth  Cen- 
tury,' especially  to  the  Introduc- 
tion, where  the  typical  position  of 
Hume  is  fully  discussed,  and  also 
to  the  last  chapter  of  the  second 
volume,  where  he  says  of  Hume 
{vol.  ii.  p.  381, 1st  ed.) :  "  Hume  was, 
in  one  sense,  far  in  advance  of  his 
time,  and  indeed  of  the  average 
opinion  of  the  present  time.  But 
the  change  may  in  many  respects 
be  described  as  a  revolt  from 
Hume's  opinions,  much  more  than 
a  development  of  them.  .  .  .  The 
history  of  philosophical  and  of  theo- 
logical opinion  in  England  is  a  his- 
tory of  gradual  decay  down  to  the 


revolutionary  era."  And  p.  444: 
"The  last  half  of  the  century  was 
pre-eminently  historical.  As  civil- 
isation progresses,  as  records  are 
better  preserved,  and  a  greater 
permanence  in  social  organisation 
makes  men  more  disposed  to  look 
beyond  their  immediate  surround- 
ings, a  tendency  to  historical  in- 
quiry is  naturally  awakened.  This 
cause  alone,  without  the  more 
philosophical  considerations  which 
might  lead  a  Hume  or  a  Gibbon 
to  turn  from  abstract  investigations 
to  historical  inquiries,  may  account 
for  the  growth  of  antiquarianism  in 
the  latter  years."  But  the  mere 
statistics  of  English  literature  in 
the  eighteenth  century  suffice  to 
prove  the  decline  of  argumenta- 
tive and  the  growth  of  realistic 
literature. 


48 


INTRODUCTION. 


25. 

Herbert 
Spencer  the 
first  Eng- 
lishman who 
has  pro- 
duced a 
system  of 
philosophy. 


26. 

Definition 
of  Lotze's 
system. 


and  have  almost  dislodged  systematic  philosophy,  England 
,has  for  the  first  time  in  her  history  produced  a  system  of 
philosophy — that  of  Mr  Herbert  Spencer ;  and  this  with 
the  distinct  understanding  that  the  object  of  philosophy 
is  the  unification  of  knowledge.1  It  is  a  remarkable  fact, 
which  will  occupy  our  close  attention  hereafter,  that  the 
unifying  principle  in  this  system  is  historical, — a  process 
of  development  now  specially  known  under  the  term 
Evolution.  This  system  forms  in  a  certain  way  a  con- 
trast to  the  last  great  system  in  German  philosophy,  that 
of  Hermann  Lotze.  Whereas  in  all  systems  of  evolution 
the  unity  of  things  is  historical,  and  has  to  be  sought  in 
their  common  origin,  Lotze  emphasised  the  truth  that 
unity  must  be  a  living  presence,  a  principle  which  ex- 
ists in  individual  things,  not  merely  a  link  which  con- 
nects them  by  proximity  in  time  or  space.  His  object 
is  to  answer  the  question,  How  can  the  human  mind 
represent  to  itself  such  a  living  unity,  in  what  ideas 


1  See  G.  H.  Lewes  ('Problems 
of  Life  and  Mind,"  1st  ed.,  vol.  i. 
p.  84),  who  says :  "  The  absence 
of  a  philosophy  in  England  dur- 
ing the  last  two  hundred  years 
has  been  a  serious  defect  in  her 
culture.  Science  she  has  had, 
and  poetry  and  literature,  rivalling 
when  not  surpassing  those  of  other 
nations.  But  a  philosophy  she  has 
not  had,  in  spite  of  philosophic 
thinkers  of  epoch-making  power. 
Hobbes,  Locke,  Berkeley,  Hume, 
have  produced  essays,  not  systems. 
There  has  been  no  noteworthy  at- 
tempt to  give  a  conception  of  the 
world,  of  man,  and  of  society, 
wrought  out  with  systematic  har- 
monising of  principles.  There  has 
not  been  an  effort  to  systematise 
the  scattered  labours  of  isolated 


thinkers.  Mr  Herbert  Spencer  is 
now  for  the  first  time  deliberately 
making  the  attempt  to  found  a 
philosophy."  And  in  his  ' History 
of  Philosophy '  (3rd  ed.,  vol.  ii.  p. 
653)  the  same  author  says  :  ' '  Mr 
Spencer  alone  of  British  thinkers 
has  organised  a  system  of  philos- 
ophy." Croom  Robertson  would 
take  exception  to  this  in  favour 
of  Hobbes,  "  who  attempted  a  task 
which  no  other  adherent  of  the 
'  mechanical  philosophy '  conceived 
— nothing  less  than  such  a  univer- 
sal construction  of  human  know- 
ledge as  would  bring  Society  and 
Man  within  the  same  principles  of 
scientific  explanation  as  were  found 
applicable  to  the  world  of  Nature'* 
(Encv.  Brit.,  9th  ed.,  vol.  xii.  p. 
39).  " 


INTRODUCTION.  49 

belonging  to  human  thought  can  this  unity  be  grasped, 
by  what  words  of  human  speech  can  it  be  expressed  ? 

Both  Mr  Herbert  Spencer's  'System'  and  Lotze's  'Micro- 
cosmus '  are  written  with  the  object  of  establishing  the 
unity  of  thought,  of  preserving  the  conviction  that  things 
exist  and  that  events  happen  in  some  intelligible  connec- 
tion, and  especially  that  the  religious  and  the  scientific 
views  of  the  world  and  life  are  reconcilable.  But  whereas 
Mr  Spencer  is  content  to  point  to  the  underlying  unity  as 
the  Unknowable,  and  then  betakes  himself  to  the  study 
and  exposition  of  the  manner  in  which  events  follow  and 
things  develop,  Lotze  considers  the  whole  of  this  part  of 
philosophy  as  merely  an  introduction  to  the  solution  of 
the  real  problem.  To  him  a  process  of  development  is 
merely  the  outer  form  in  which  some  real  substance  pre- 
sents itself,  a  mechanical  method  by  which  something  of 
higher  value  is  accomplished.  He  admits  the  all-pervad- 
ing rule  of  such  a  mechanism,  but  he  urges  the  necessity 
of  finding  the  substance  itself,  and  of  gaining  a  view  of 
the  end  and  aim  which  is  to  be  attained  by  this  array  of 
processes,  by  this  parade  of  mechanical  means,  of  the  in- 
terest that  attaches  to  them,  and  the  result  which  is  to  be 
secured.1  Knowing  the  mechanism  by  which  a  certain 
object  is  accomplished,  we  may  be  able  to  calculate  pheno- 
mena and  events,  but  to  understand 2  them  requires  a 


1  The  earliest  passage  in  which 
Lotze  gives  us  a  pretty  complete 
idea  of  his  philosophical  methods 
and  aims  is  to  be  found  in  his  pol- 
emical pamphlet  against  Fichte  the 
younger  ('Streitschriften,'  Leipzig, 
1857,  p.  52  sqq.)  He  there  also 
reviews  his  attitude  to  the  ideal- 
istic school  of  German  Philosophy 


and  to  Herbart,  whose  follower  he 
refuses  to  be  called  (ibid.,  p.  5  sq.) 
It  is  evident  that  at  that  time  his 
system  was  not  yet  definitely  set- 
tled in  his  mind  (p.  58). 

'2  The  difference  between  calcula- 
ting and  understanding  phenomena 
is  probably  to  be  traced  to  Leibniz. 
Lotze  emphasises  this  difference. 


VOL.  I.  D 


50  INTRODUCTION. 

further  knowledge  of  the  worth  of  the  object  which  is 
accomplished,  of  the  result  which  is  gained  by  the  calcu- 
lation. It  is  one  thing  to  be  able  to  trace  the  mechanical 
conditions  upon  which  the  accuracy  of  a  clock  depends ; 
it  is  another  to  mark  the  hour  which  the  clock  strikes, 
and  to  note  the  time  which  it  measures  out  to  us  for  our 
work.  Curiosity  will  lead  a  child  to  pry  into  the  former  ; 
but  the  latter  depends  on  our  appreciation  of  the  objects 
of  life  and  the  seriousness  of  our  duties. 
27.  When  Lotze  undertook  to  write  the  '  Microcosmus,'  he 

Lotze's  re-  -ici-iii 

lation  to       referred  to  two  great  works  of  a  kindred  tendency.     Both 

Herder's 

'ideen.1  attempted,  yet  in  very  different  ways,  to  give  a  compre- 
hensive view  of  a  large  field  of  scattered  phenomena,  to 
take  in  at  a  glance  the  entire  scheme  of  a  great  world  of 
facts.  The  earlier  of  the  two  belonged  to  the  last  century 
and  was  concerned  with  history,  with  the  uniting  bond  of 
all  human  development.  For  this  Herder,  in  his  '  Ideen 
zur  Philosophic  der  Geschichte  der  Menschheit,'  had,  if  not 
invented,  yet  endowed  the  term  Humanity  with  a  specific 
pregnancy,  meaning  by  it  the  unity  of  all  human  interests 
in  their  social  and  historical  development — an  idea  which 
since  Leibniz  has  governed  German  literature.1  The  other 

See,  inter  alia,  the  closing  para-  last  two  volumes  of  his  '  Literatur- 
graph  of  the  first  volume  of  the  geschichte  des  ISten  Jahrhunderts.' 
'System  der  Philosophic '  (1st  ed. ,  !  I  quote  from  the  2nd  edition, 
Leipzig,  1874).  I  cannot  omit  to  Braunschweig,  1872.  Herder  had 
notice  here  the  extraordinary  and  inherited  the  spirit  of  Leibniz  (see, 
misleading  misprint  in  Erdmann's  inter  alia,  the  concluding  chapter 
quotation  of  this  passage  :  see  his  of  rny  essay  on  Leibniz,  in  Black- 
valuable  '  Geschichte  der  Philoso-  wood's  Philosophical  Classics,  Edin- 
phie'  (3rd  ed.,  Berlin,  1878,  vol.  ii.  !  burgh,  1884).  Herder  formed  a 
p.  861).  where  instead  of  bereckncn,  kind  of  centre  of  thought,  inas- 
to  calculate,  we  read  bezeichnen,  to  much  as  he  gathered  up  in  his  own 
designate  !  mind  and  writings  the  influences  of 
1  The  history  of  this  idea  has  j  Leibniz,  Rousseau,  and  the  Eng- 
been  written  by  Hettner  in  the  '  lish  writers  of  the  eighteenth  cen- 


INTRODUCTION. 


51 


great  work  was  that  of  A.  v.  Humboldt,  who  in  the  course       as. 

Lotze's  re- 

or  a  long  career,  peculiarly  favoured  by  opportunities  for  utionto 
studying  Nature  on  an  extensive  scale,  and  for  appreciating  * 
the  detail  of  modern  research,  of  which  he  was  an  illustrious 
representative,  had  never  lost  sight  of  the  all-pervading 
unity.1     In  an  elevated  style,  in  which  poetry  and  science 


tury,  together  with  classical  influ- 
ences and  new  inspirations  drawn 
from  the  popular  song-literature  of 
all  nations.  Hettner  says  (see  last 
volume  but  one,  p.  7) :  "  Herder 
applied  Rousseau's  gospel  of  Nature 
to  the  demands  of  poetical  sense 
and  creation.  Thus  he  has  become 
essentially  the  forerunner  of  the 
new  school  of  poets  :  the  last  fetters 
of  the  moralising  style  by  which 
even  Lessing  was  still  hampered 
fell,  and  through  the  scientific  study 
of  the  beginnings  and  development 
of  human  culture  he  became  the 
founder  of  a  new  science  of  Lan- 
guage, Religion,  and  History,  in  the 
lines  of  which  we  are  still  advanc- 
ing." And  p.  101  :  "  Herder  does 
not  belong  to  the  classics  of  the 
style  of  Winckelmann,  Lessiug, 
Kant,  Goethe,  and  Schiller ;  he  is 
everywhere  only  suggestive,  hardly 
anywhere  conclusive  and  final.  For 
this  reason  his  writings  are  to  some 
extent  antiquated.  Nevertheless 
Herder  is  one  of  our  most  im- 
portant and  influential  spiritual 
heroes.  Herder  made  so  deep  an 
impression  on  his  age  that  the 
great  poetry  of  Goethe  and  Schiller, 
the  so-called  Romantic  School,  the 
philosophies  of  Schelling  and  Hegel, 
cannot  be  imagined  without  Herder 
as  the  precursor."  The  fourth 
volume  of  Gervinus,  '  Geschichte 
der  deutschen  Dichtung,'  contains 
likewise  a  very  important  chapter 
on  Herder.  But  the  great  authority 
on  Herder  is  R.  Haym,  '  Herder  nach 
seinern  Leben  uud  seinen  Werken ' 
(Berlin,  2  vols.,  1880  and  1885). 


From  the  unpublished  literary 
notes,  correspondences,  and  diaries 
of  Herder,  which  Haym  inspected, 
it  is  evident  that  the  great  idea  of 
writing  a  History  of  Humanity 
originated  in  Herder's  mind  as  far 
back  as  the  year  1769,  on  a  voyage 
from  Riga  to  Nantes  (on  the  way 
to  Paris).  His  diary  closes  thus : 
"  History  of  the  progress  and  of  the 

i  powers  of  the  human  mind  in  the 
concurrence  of  whole  ages  and 
nations — a  spirit,  a  good  demon,  has 

i  exhorted  me  to  do  this.  Be  that 
my  life's  work,  History,  work  !" 

The  first  attempt  to  carry  out 
his  great  idea  was  published  by 
Herder  in  the  year  1774,  with  the 
title  :  '  Auch  eine  Philosophic  der 
Geschichte  zur  Bildung  der  Mensch- 
heit.'  Herder  was  then  in  his 
thirtieth  year.  His  chief  work 
appeared  ten  years  later  (1784),  with 
the  title  '  Ideen  zur  Geschichte  der 
Menschheit.'  Herder  died  in  1803. 
Goethe's  '  Faust,'  which  is  an  at- 
tempt to  deal  with  the  highest 
problems  of  human  interest,  the 
problems  of  knowledge,  evil,  sin, 
and  redemption,  as  they  appear  in 
the  history  of  a  great  individual, 
not  of  the  race,  had  its  first  begin- 
nings about  the  same  time  as  Her- 
der's '  Histoiy  of  Mankind.'  But 
the  work  was  not  finished  till  a  year 
before  Goethe's  death  in  1831. 

1  Alex.  v.  Humboldt,  '  Kosmos. 
Entwurf  einer  physischen  Welt- 
beschreibung,'  1845.  Like  Her- 
der's great  work  on  the  '  History  of 
Humanity'  and  Goethe's  'Faust,' 
Humboldt's  '  Kosmos '  occupied  a 


52  INTRODUCTION. 

are  happily  blended,  he  essayed  in  the  evening  of  life  to 
unroll  before  the  gaze  of  his  readers  a  picture  of  the 
grand  features  of  nature  as  his  mind  had  viewed  them 
from  the  elevated  regions  of  scientific  study,  and  his  eyes 
from  the  heights  of  Chimborazo. 

In  the  great  picture  of  the  world,  in  the  vast  changes 
of  the  universe,  where  is  man  with  his  life  and  his  in- 
terests ?  In  the  huge  Kosmos  where  is  the  Microcosmus  ? 
^  This  question  naturally  presented  itself  to  the  mind  of 
*•'  Lotze.  "  It  is  not,"  he  tells  us,  "  the  all-embracing '  kos- 
mos '  of  the  universe  which  we  wish  to  describe  again  on 
the  model  which  has  been  given  to  our  nation.  As  the 
features  of  that  great  world -portrait  sink  deeper  into 
general  consciousness,  so  much  more  vividly  will  they 
lead  us  back  to  our  own  selves,  suggesting  anew  the 
question,  What  significance  belongs  to  man  and  human 
life  with  its  lasting  characteristics  and  the  changing 


long  period  in  the  life  of  its  author.  '  Die  Ansichten  der  Xatur1  (1808)  ; 

Goethe's  '  Faust '  deals  with  the  in-  also  bj  Georg  Forster  (1754-1794), 

dividual  problem,  Herder's  '  Ideen'  who  wrote  an  account  of  the  second 

with  the  problem  of   the  race   or  voyage  of  Captain  Cook  round  the 

mankind,     Humboldt's     '  Kosmos '  world,  whom  he  accompanied  with 


with  the  same  problem  as  referring 
to  the  world,  the  universe.  In  the 
preface  Humboldt  confesses  "  that 
the  image  of  his  work  had  stood 
before  his  mind's  eye  in  undefined 
outlines  for  nearly  half  a  century :: : 
ef.  what  Goethe  says  in  the  dedica- 
tion to  'Faust'  (written  probablv 
after  1797)  :— 


his  father.  "  He  conceived  of  na- 
ture as  a  living  whole ;  his  account 
is  almost  the  first  example  of  the 
glowing  yet  faithful  description  of 
natural  phenomena,  which  has  since 
made  the  knowledge  of  them  the 
common  propertv  of  the  educated 
world  "  (R.  Garnett  in  'Ency.  Brit.,' 
art.  "  Forster ").  Humboldt  con- 


.  _  fesses  to  have  received  from   him 

Agam  ye  come,  ye  ]  „  ^  ]ebhafte3te  Anregung  zu  wei- 

A*  e*rty  to  my  clouded  sight  ye  shone,"  ten  Unternehmungen  "  ('  Koemos,' 

*c-  voL  L  p.  345,  also  voL  ii.  p.  65.  and 

especially  voL  iL  p.  72,  where  in- 

The  view  of  the  universe  which  was  cidentally  also  Darwin's  narrative 

given  in  Humboldt's  '  Kosmos '  was  of  the  "  Adventure r>  and  "Beagle" 

prepared   by   his  own  publication,  is  mentioned). 


INTRODUCTION. 


53 


course  of  its  history  in  the  great  totality  of  nature  ? " l 
And  in  collecting  the  answers  to  this  question  which 
suggest  themselves  both  in  and  outside*  of  the  study, 
Lotze  professes  only  to  renew  the  enterprise  brilliantly 
begun  by  Herder  in  his  '  Ideen  zur  Geschichte  der 
Menschheit.'  Both  Herder's  '  Ideen '  and  Humboldt's 
'  Kosmos  '  belong  to  the  age  in  which  philosophy  and 
poetry  largely  influenced  science  and  history.  Many  may 
now  think  it  premature  or  altogether  impossible  to  try 
to  combine  the  detailed  studies  of  modern  science  and 
modern  history  with  the  comprehensive  view  demanded 
by  philosophers  and  poets,  or  to  grope  through  the  laby- 
rinth of  external  phenomena  and  events  to  their  under- 
lying significance  and  unity.  They  may,  whilst  fully 
maintaining  the  existence  of  an  all -pervading  power, 
nevertheless  relegate  it  with  Mr  Spencer  to  the  region 
of  the  Unknowable.2  Without  desiring  at  present  to 


1  Microcosmus,  1st  ed.,  Leipzig, 
1856,  Preface.  Hermann  Lotze  was 
Lorn  in  1817,  and  died  in  1881. 
His  first  philosophical  essay  of  im- 
portance was  the  '  Metaphysik ' 
(Leipzig,  1841). 

'2  Herbert  Spencer's  Philosophy 
•of  the  "  Unknowable  "  is  laid  down 
in  his  Introduction  to  '  First  Prin- 
ciples.' I  believe  the  first  appear- 
ance of  the  first  part  of  this  book 
was  in  1860,  and  the  first  collected 
publication  in  the  year  1867.  In 
defining  the  region  of  the  Know- 
able  an  opposite  course  has  been 
adopted  by  Emil  du  Bois-Reymond, 
who  in  a  series  of  addresses  and 
articles,  now  collected  in  two  vol- 
umes with  the  title  'Reden'  (Ber- 
lin, 1886  and  1887),  tried  to  lead 
up  to  the  limits  which  are  fixed 
around  scientific  knowledge.  The 
purport  of  his  teaching  on  the 


highest  "  World-problem  "  is  con- 
tained in  the  four  words,  ignoramus, 
ignorabimus,  dubitcmus,  laboremus. 
The  first  of  these  addresses,  which 
are  full  of  brilliant  suggestions  and 
vivid  illustrations,  furnishing  in  the 
notes  especially  an  invaluable  store 
of  historical  references  on  the  sub- 
ject of  the  philosophy  of  the  sci- 
ences, was  delivered  at  the  forty  - 
fifth  meeting  of  the  German  "Na- 
turforscher  und  Aertze,"  and  pub- 
lished at  Leipzig,  August  1872,  with 
the  title  '  Die  Grenzen  des  Natur- 
erkennens.'  It  made  a  great  sensa- 
tion, and  was  translated  into  several 
languages.  It  was  followed  some 
years  later  by  an  address  delivered 
in  the  Berlin  Academy,  1880,  and 
published  with  the  title  '  Die  sieben 
Weltriithsel. '  If  H.  Spencer's  phil- 
osophy is  termed  the  philosophy 
of  the  Unknowable,  Du  Bois-Rey- 


54 


INTRODUCTION. 


criticise  the  weighty  considerations  which  have  led  them 
to  a  view  so  modest  and  resigned,  I  propose  in  the 
sequel  to  test  within  narrower  limits,  and  by  what 
seems  to  me  a  novel  method,  the  validity  of  the  con- 
viction that  a  true  understanding  of  phenomena  and 
events  can  be  attained  only  by  viewing  them  in  their 
interdependence  and  collective  effect.  If  anything  in 
the  wide  expanse  of  physical  and  mental  life  deserves 
to  be  considered  as  one  and  indivisible,  it  is  surely 
human  thought  in  its  various  branches  and  manifesta- 
tions. The  attempt  to  trace  its  origin  in  the  early  ages 
of  civilisation,  or  to  foreshadow  the  end  which  it  is 
slowly  approaching,  may  indeed  be  impossible ;  but  of 
the  age  to  which  we  belong,  and  the  literature  of 
which  we  have  witnessed  the  growth,  we  may  claim  to 
possess  a  deeper  knowledge.  Astronomers  have  suc- 
ceeded in  gaining  a  view  of  immense  and  distant  orbits 
by  minutely  observing  and  tracing  merely  an  insignifi- 
cant portion 1  which  came  within  their  view.  Com- 
parative anatomy  teaches  how  from  a  few  surviving 
links  to  construct  the  whole  framework  of  an  organism. 
I  propose  to  apply  a  similar  method  to  the  small  portion 


mond's  may  be  termed  the  philo- 
sophy of  the  Limits  of  the  Know- 
able.  Both  views  form  a  contrast 
to  Lotze's  philosophy. 

1  The  most  brilliant  example  of 
this  is  the  discovery  of  the  planet 
Ceres  by  Piazzi  at  Palermo  in  the 
New  Year's  night  of  1801  ;  the  in- 
vention of  special  methods  for  cal- 
culating the  orbit  of  this  planet, 
which  had  been  lost,  by  Gauss  in  the 
course  of  1801;  ami  the  rediscovery 
of  it  by  Olbers,  aided  by  Gauss's 
ephemeris,  in  the  New  Year's  night 


of  1802.  After  the  discovery  of  this 
first  of  the  small  planets,  but  before 
it  was  known  in  Germany,  Hegel 
published  his  '  Dissertatio  plrilo- 
sophica  de  orbitis  planetarum,1  in 
which  he  ridiculed  the  search  for 
new  planets,  but  which  Duke  Ern- 
est of  Gotha  sent  to  the  astrono- 
mer Zach  with  the  superscription, 
"  Monumentum  insanisc  sseculi  de- 
cimi  noni."  See  R.  Wolf,  Ge~ 
schichte  der  Astronomic,  Miinchen,. 
1877,  p.  684  sqq. 


INTRODUCTION.  55 

of  mental  progress  of  which  I  have  been  able  to  take 
personal  notice  and  of  which  I  have  felt  the  immediate 
personal  influence.  A  tracing  as  concisely  as  possible 
of  this  comparatively  small  portion  of  the  course  of 
European  thought  may  be  the  first  approximation  to 
more  accurate  delineations,  which  .  themselves  will  be 
the  means  of  gradually  gaining  a  truer  idea  of  the  pur- 
port and  significance  that  belong  to  the  larger  dimen- 
sions of  the  mental  life  of  mankind. 

This  life  does  not  consist  in  the  accumulated  knowledge 
of  our  century,  not  in  the  results  of  scientific  inquiry  de- 
posited in  libraries  and  museums,  not  in  the  many  schools 
for  learning  and  study,  not  in  educational  and  social  re- 
forms, least  of  all  in  political  and  economic  institutions. 
These  are  all  external  objects,  which  are  capable  of  being 
described  or  photographed  like  the  external  objects  of 
nature.  The  mental  life  of  mankind  consists  in  the  inner  so. 

What  the 


processes  of  reflection,  by  which  these  external  objects  have 
been  produced,  by  which  man  has  been  able  to  add  to  the  cc 
physical  creation  of  nature  a  new  creation  of  his  own,  by 
which  he  has  been  able  to  change  the  face  of  the  earth, 
and  endow  the  objects  of  nature  with  an  ideal  meaning. 
To  this  end  he  is  always  inventing  and  using  methods 
which  change,  suggesting  and  applying  principles  which 
turn  out  to  be  half  true  or  totally  fallacious,  guessing  at 
results  and  aims  which  have  to  be  abandoned,  inventing 
theories  which  are  short-lived  —  in  fact,  erecting  scaffold- 
ings with  the  help  of  which  he  raises  the  structures  of 
Society,  Art,  and  Science  :  these  remain  as  the  historical 
testimonies  of  his  activity  ;  the  scaffoldings  are  removed  as 
of  merely  transient  and  temporary  value  ;  and  yet  they 


56  INTRODUCTION. 

alone  constitute  the  mental  life  which  interests  us.  Only 
so  far  as  we  have  taken  part  in  building  the  scaffolding, 
only  in  so  far  as  we  have  witnessed  the  many  contrivances 
which  have  been  used,  only  HI  so  far  as  we  have  seen  the 
growth  of  any  structure  from  small  beginnings,  from  the 
first  sketch  of  the  architect,  can  we  say  that  we  know 
something  of  the  mental  life  which  lies  hidden  in  and 
behind  those  external  signs  and  documents.  A  closer 
study  of  what  we  ourselves  have  witnessed  is  thus  the 
only  way  of  attaining  some  insight  into  the  workings  of 
the  mind  —  the  spiritual  life  of  mankind.  We  shall  pres- 
ently find  that  in  science  as  well  as  in  philosophy  every 
period  starts  from  certain  assumptions  and  proceeds  ac- 
31.  cording  to  certain  methods,  that  certain  habits  of  thought 

Methods,        ,  ,  _ 

the  most      become  general,  and  certain  views  become  accepted  :  but  in 

approved, 

da"eandir     *ke  course  °f  one  or  kwo  generations  we  find  those  assurnp- 


ceasetobe.  ^jcms  questioned,  those  methods  criticised,  a  new  habit  of 
thought  introduced,  and  those  general  views  which  seemed 
so  natural  and  convenient  giving  way  to  new  and  altered 
ones.  The  whole  fabric  of  society,  the  whole  structure  of 
science  and  knowledge,  all  the  applications  of  art,  have  to 
be  remodelled  on  new  principles,  and  to  meet  our  changed 
32.  demands.  Few  indeed,  very  few,  of  the  old  creations 
remain.  One  or  two  so-called  laws  of  science  that  sur- 

inheritall 

of  the  past;  vivo,  a  few  dozen  books  that  are  re-edited,  half-a-dozen 

it  discards 

works  of  art  and  one  or  two  great  poems,  —  this  is  about 
all  that  our  century  will  at  its  close  have  preserved  as  the 
living  inheritance  of  its  early  years  :  all  the  others  will  be 
relegated  to  the  growing  bulk  of  historical  records.  Pos- 
sessed of  merely  monumental  interest  as  documents  of  a 
bygone  life,  these  creations  had  to  be  left  aside  as  incap- 


INTRODUCTION.  5  7 

able  of  marking  or  guiding  any  longer  our  onward  career. 
A  few  centuries  lapse,  and  posterity  will  look  upon  them 
as  we  do  on  the  huge  monuments  of  early  Eastern  civili- 
sation, on  the  Sphinx  in  the  desert  or  the  Pyramids  of 
Egypt,  wondering  by  what  ingenious  contrivances  they 
were  raised,  what  amount  of  human  work  and  suffering 
they  represent,  or  what  idea  lived  in  the  minds  of  those 
who  planned  and  placed  them  where  they  still  remain. 

III. 

It  is  the  privilege  of  art  to  represent  at  a  glance  the        i. 

......  Necessity  of 

whole  oi  its  object,  and  thus  to  produce  at  once  a  total  choosing  a 

road. 

effect  on  the  mind  of  the  beholder.  Closer  scrutiny  may 
follow  and  may  show  how  the  various  parts  support 
the  whole,  how  the  uniting  idea  is  revealed  in  all  the 
manifold  detail  of  the  component  elements :  still  the  im- 
pression of  the  whole  remains  and  supplies  the  key  for 
the  comprehension  of  every  part.  Literature,  science,  and 
history  are  denied  this  privilege  of  presenting  their  ob- 
jects in  their  entirety,  and  thus  giving  from  the  outset  a 
commanding  view,  a  leading  and  abiding  impression  of  the 
whole.  We  have  to  ask  the  student  to  follow  us  patiently 
by  an  isolated  path  to  the  summit :  many  ways  lead  to  it, 
.and  we  may  err  in  the  choice  of  the  right  and  convenient 
one.  Even  if  we  succeed  in  reaching  the  central  position, 
we  may  have  fatigued  the  reader  on  the  road  or  produced 
sensations  which  prevent  the  unbiassed  contemplation  of 
the  whole  view  when  it  is  presented.  With  us  the  whole 
is  only  the  sum  of  its  many  parts,  whereas  with  the  artist 
.the  parts  are  merely  fractions  of  a  united  whole.  In 


58 


INTRODUCTION. 


2. 

Some  peri- 
ods of  his- 
tory  take 

from  some6 


treating  of  the  thought  of  the  century,  even  within  the 
narrow  limits  which  have  been  prescribed,  I  am  met  with 
similar  difficulties.  In  the  large  circumference  of  the 
domain  of  thought  I  have  to  choose  a  starting-point  and 
to  construct  a  road  which  may  lead  to  the  central  position, 
hoping  there  to  gain  a  comprehensive  view  of  the  whole. 
Some  periods  of  history  are  characterised  by  one  great 
and  central  movement  which  absorbs  all  active  forces 
an(^  a^  intellectual  and  imaginative  power,  making 
them  either  subservient  to  one  end  and  purpose,  and 
helpful  in  the  elaboration  of  one  idea;  or  else  forcing 
them  into  opposition,  where  they  testify  equally  to  the 
importance  of  this  central  movement.  Such  periods 
were,  for  instance,  the  long  centuries  of  Jewish  history, 
the  early  age  of  the  Christian  Church,  the  period  of  the 
culmination  of  Papal  power,  the  Reformation,  the  French 
Revolution.  In  studying  the  thought  of  such  ages,  we 
are  not  at  a  loss  where  to  find  the  leading  idea,  —  we 
easily  fix  the  centre  of  the  vortex  which  draws  into  its 
motion  all  the  existing  forces,  all  genius  and  all  talent. 
In  an  age  like  that  of  the  Reformation  we  can  speak  of 
the  Politics  of  the  Reformation,  the  Religion  of  the  Refor- 
mation, the  Philosophy,  Literature,  and  Art  of  the  Refor- 
mation, and  we  are  pretty  sure  to  embrace  under  these 
various  heads  an  account  of  all  the  mental  progress  and 
to  trace  all  the  thought  of  that  age,  be  it  friendly  or  anta- 
3.  gonistic.  It  is  evident  that  no  such  central  event,  no  such 
e\°nthiour  all-absorbing  vortex  of  motion,  exists  in  the  period  which 

r._-r. 

we  have  lived  through.  The  uniting  bond,  if  it  exists,  lies 
much  deeper  ;  the  problem  we  have  been  engaged  in  solv- 
ing, the  prize  we  are  fighting  for,  does  not  present  itself  on 


INTRODUCTION. 


59 


the  surface ;  it  is  not  explicitly  stated,  it  must  be  implied 
rather  than  defined.  The  great  object  of  our  life  and 
labour  has  not  been  clear  to  us,  as  it  seemed  clear  to  those 
who  lived  during  the  Reformation  or  the  Eevolution,  other- 
wise we  should  not  have  philosophies  of  the  Unconscious 
and  of  the  Unknowable,  and  the  century  would  not  end 
in  asking,  Is  life  worth  living  ? 

Then,  again,  we  find  in  history  long  periods  of  quiet 
development,  where  men's  minds  seemingly  run  very  much 
in  the  same  direction,  exhibiting  a  general  tendency  of 
ideas,  the  spreading  of  a  defined  habit  of  thought  and  of 
simple  methods,  the  application  of  a  few  principles  :  such 
a  period  was  that  preceding  the  French  Eevolution,  the 
greater  part  of  the  eighteenth  century.  It  has  therefore 
been  easy  to  characterise  that  century :  it  has  been 
termed  the  philosophical  century,  the  century  of  the 
Aufklarung,  the  century  of  Voltaire.1  No  such  one 


1  The  first  who  reviewed  the 
literature  of  the  eighteenth  century 
from  an  international  point  of  view 
was  Villemaiu,  who  as  early  as  1820 
was  engaged  in  lecturing  at  the 
Sorbonne  before  the  ilite  of  the 
rising  literary  generation  of  France 
on  the  literature  of  the  eighteenth 
century,  taking  France  as  the  centre, 
and  showing  the  influence  of  foreign 
literature,  especially  English,  as  like- 
wise the  reaction  of  French  ideas 
abroad.  He  was  too  early  to  recog- 
nise the  true  meaning  of  the  new 
spirit  which  had  then  already  gone 
forth  from  Germany.  In  this  respect 
his  '  Cours  de  Litterature  franfaise,' 
published  in  1828  and  republished  in 
1864,  remains  incomplete.  Schlosser 
next  attempted  to  present  in  his 
'  Geschichte  des  achtzehnten  Jahr- 
hunderts,'  after  the  manner  of 
Gibbon,  a  picture  of  the  combined 


political  and  literary  work  of  the 
last  century.  The  first  draft  of  it 
appeared  in  1824,  after  Schlosser 
had  passed  two  years  in  Paris,  where 
no  doubt  he  must  have  come  under 
the  influence  of  Villemain.  The 
work  itself  began  to  appear  in  1826,. 
and  was  finished  in  i848.  It  is 
considered  to  be  Schlosser's  greatest 
work,  and  had  a  large  circulation. 
The  connection  of  political  and 
literary  history  was  studied  by 
Gervinus,  who  with  Hiiusser  is 
usually  counted  as  a  pupil  of 
Schlosser.  But  the  great  work 
which  Villemain  had  begun  and 
Schlosser  taken  up  was  adequately 
carried  out  by  Hettner,  who  in 
his  '  Literaturgeschichte  des  acht- 
zehnten Jahrhunderts '  conceived 
the  whole  intellectual  movement  of 
that  age  as  a  battle  for  enlighten- 
i  meirt^Kampfder  Aufklaruny).  The 


60 


INTRODUCTION. 


history  of 
philosophy  \ 


term  can  be  applied  to  our  age,  no  one  name  can  be 
found  which  carries  with  it  the  recognition  of  all  the 
many  interests  which  surround  us. 

4.  It  has  been  suggested  by  some  that  the  history  of 

of  thought  thought  is  equivalent  to  the  history  of  philosophy ;  that 
the  different  philosophical  systems  and  theories  exhibit 
in  the  abstract  the  course  which  ideas  have  taken  in  an 
age.1  A  history  of  thought  in  the  nineteenth  century 
would  thus  mean  a  history  of  nineteenth  century  philo- 
sophy. There  have  indeed  been  plenty  of  philosophies 
and  systems  during  our  period,  but  in  spite  of  their 
great  number  and  variety — ranging  from  the  extreme 
idealism  of  Fichte  to  the  equally  extreme  materialism 
of  Biichner 2 — we  feel  that  they  do  not  cover  the  whole 
area  of  thought.  The  period  in  our  century  which  in 
England  was  most  barren  in  philosophy,  the  first  forty 
years,  produced  an  entirely  new  literature  and  a  novel 
conception  of  art,  both  containing  new  sources  of  mental 
life,  though  they  have  hardly  yet  found  expression  in  any 
philosophical  system.  Equally  barren  in  speculation  was 
France  during  the  Eestoration;  yet  there,  too,  was  a 


latter  part  of  his  work  deals  with  I 
the  reaction  against  Aufkldruivj 
and  "  Rationalism "  as  it  began  in  ' 
England,  and  was  represented  on 
the  Continent  by  Rousseau  and 
the  earlier  ideals  of  the  French 
Revolution.  Through  Rousseau  and 
the  Revolution  the  growing  in- 
fluence of  the  new  spirit  of  English 
literature  was  overpowered  and  lost 
for  the  Continent.  And,  as  we  have 
to  regret  in  Villemain  his  neglect 
-of  the  new  life  of  Germany,  so  we 
"have  to  deplore  that  Hettner  fol- 
lowed the  developments  of  Rational- 
ism and  Aufkliirung  only  in  the 


form  they  assumed  in  Germany, 
neglecting  to  notice  the  contem- 
porary growth  of  the  new  life  in 
English  Literature  and  Art,  to 
which,  in  fact,  no  German  historian 
has  as  yet  done  justice. 

1  See  especially  Hegel's  Lectures 
on  the  History  of  Philosophy  in  his 
collected  works,  vol.  xiii.  p.  68  sqq. 
(Complete  edition,  Berlin,  1832.) 

2  The    principal   publications   of 
this  school  are  Vogt, '  Physiologische 
Briefe,' 1845-47  ;  Moleschott,  'Der 
Kreislauf  des  Lebens,'  1852  ;  Biich- 
ner, 'Kraft  uud  Stoff,'  1855. 


INTRODUCTION. 


61 


5. 
Goethe's 


brilliant  era  of  literature,  and  the  whole  of  Europe  was 
illuminated  by  the  light  of  science  which  emanated  from 
Paris  during  the  first  third  of  this  century.  History  of 
philosophy  has  little  to  say  about  Goethe,  though  his  work  in- 
work  embodies  for  us  probably  the  deepest  thought  of  thought  of 
modern  times.  Again,  the  only  great  and  novel  system  the  century> 
of  philosophy  which  France  has  produced  during  this 
century  is  that  of  Comte,  but  it  has  had  only  small 
influence  in  its  own  country ;  and  who  would  say  that 
it  reflects  French  thought  of  the  period  as  Voltaire 
and  Montesquieu  reflected  the  thought  of  the  last 
century  ?  Hegel  himself,  who  was  intent  upon  tracing 
the  working  of  the  human  mind  in  the  systems  of 
philosophy,  declared  that  philosophy  is  the  latest  fruit 
of  civilisation, — that  the  special  idea  which  governs  any 
period  is  already  dying  out  when  it  appears  in  a  system.1 


1  The  principal  passage  expound- 
ing this  idea  of  Hegel's  is  to  be 
found  in  the  introduction  to  the 
course  of  lectures  which  he  delivered 
at  Berlin  repeatedly  during  the  years 
1816  to  1830.  See  his  collected 
works,  vol.  xiii.  p.  66  :  "  Philosophy 
makes  its  appearance  at  the  time 
when  the  mind  of  a  nation  has 
worked  itself  out  of  the  indifferent 
dulness  of  the  early  life  of  nature, 
as  well  as  out  of  the  period  of  pas- 
sionate interest ;  inasmuch  as  the 
direction  towards  detail  has  spent 
itself,  the  mind  transcends  its 
natural  form — it  passes  on  from 
practical  morals,  from  the  force  of 
real  life  to  reflection  and  compre- 
hension. The  consequence  is,  that 
it  attacks  this  actual  form  of  exist- 
ence, these  morals,  this  faith,  and 
disturbs  them  ;  and  with  this  conies 
the  period  of  decay.  The  further 
stage  is,  that  thought  tries  to  collect 
itself.  One  may  say,  that  where  a 


people  has  come  out  of  its  concrete 
forms  of  life,  where  distinction  and 
separation  of  classes  has  set  in, 
where  the  nation  approaches  its 
fall,  where  a  rupture  has  taken 
place  between  the  inner  desires  and 
the  external  reality,  where  the  rul- 
ing form  of  religion,  &c.,  &c.,  does 
not  satisfy,  where  the  mind  shows 
indifference  towards  its  living  exist- 
ence or  lingers  discontentedly  in  it, 
where  moral  life  is  in  dissolution — 
then  only  does  one  philosophise. 
The  soul  takes  refuge  in  the  realms 
of  thought,  and  in  opposition  to  the 
real  world  it  creates  a  world  of  ideas. 
Philosophy  is  then  the  reparation  of 
the  mischief  which  thought  has  be- 
gun. Philosophy  begins  with  the 
decline  of  a  real  world  :  when  she 
appears  with  her  abstractions,  paint- 
ing grey  in  grey,  then  the  freshness 
of  youth  and  life  is  already  gone  ; 
and  her  reconciliation  is  not  one  in 
reality,  but  in  an  ideal  world." 


62  INTRODUCTION. 

e.        This  means  that  philosophy  is  retrospective :  it  sums  up, 

Philosophy 

retrospec-     it  criticises,  it  does  not  prefigure  the  future.     The  correct- 

tive. 

ness  of  this  proposition  may  be  doubted.  We  shall  have 
to  deal  with  it  in  another  place.  At  present  it  reminds 
us  that  thought,  in  the  sense  in  which  we  take  it,  cannot 
be  identified  with  philosophy,  and  hence  a  history  of 
philosophy  in  the  nineteenth  century  is  not  identical 
with  a  history  of  its  thought.  There  is  indeed  a  sense 
in  which  the  word  philosophy  is  sometimes  used,  when 
it  approaches  more  nearly  to  the  meaning  of  the  word 
thought,  as  we  intend  to  use  it.  Whewell  has  in  this 
sense  written  the  philosophy  of  the  inductive  sciences, 
meaning  to  trace  in  that  work  the  processes  of  thought 
which  are  consciously  or  unconsciously  employed  in 
scientific  research  and  reasoning,  and  which  lead  to 
7.  progress  in  science.  Something  similar  might  be  at- 

When  does  ... 

thought       tempted  in  regard  to  art,  commerce,  politics,  government, 

mean  philo- 
sophy? religion,  and  literature  generally.  In  every  case  philo- 
sophy would  simply  mean  the  peculiar  way  of  thinking 
and  reasoning  which  is  adopted  in  these  various  branches 
of  practical  or  intellectual  life.  This  is,  however,  not  the 
sense  in  which  the  word  philosophy  is  generally  used. 
It  generally  denotes  something  more  than  a  statement  of 
method  or  a  rationale  of  ideas  and  reflections  ;  it  denotes 
a  definite  theory,  an  explanation  of  a  larger  or  smaller 
circle  of  phenomena.  As  such  it  certainly  forms  a  part 
of  the  thought  of  the  century,  probably  the  most  in- 
teresting and  fascinating  part ;  but  it  is  also  that 
which  is  most  liable  to  change,  most  subject  to  discus- 
sion ;  whereas  the  other  more  hidden  thoughts  and  reason- 
ings form,  as  it  were,  the  ground  upon  which  all  the 


INTRODUCTION.  63 

intellectual,  artistic,  and  practical  achievements  of  the  age 
rest. 

It  would  thus  appear  as  if  an  account  of  the  thought  of        s. 

Inquiry  into 

the  century  might  naturally  divide  itself  into  two  separate  j^^t  of 
investigations.  In  the  first  place,  we  should  regard  thought  tw^ 
merely  as  a  means  to  an  end,  as  the  method  adopted  to 
attain  a  certain  purpose,  be  it  practical  or  theoretical.  It 
would  mean  the  peculiar  kind  of  reasoning  which  has  been 
employed  in  the  search  for  knowledge  or  in  its  useful 
application.  As  all  reasoning  starts  from  certain  assump- 
tions, called  premisses,  or  principles,  or  axioms,  and  pro- 
gresses from  these  by  certain  methods,  this  portion  of  our 
task  would  divide  itself  again  into  a  statement  of  the 
principles  which  underlie,  and  an  account  of  the  methods 
which  have  guided,  theoretical  and  practical  reasoning. 
But  thought  does  not  exist  merely  for  the  sake  of  in- 
creasing our  knowledge  of  things  and  of  applying  this  to 
practical  purposes.  Occupied  in  this  way  merely,  it  re- 
mains fragmentary,  incomplete,  and  not  infrequently  it 
reveals  contradictions.  Even  those  who  devote  themselves 
purely  to  detailed  research  or  to  practical  work  are  again 
and  again  compelled  to  take  a  wider  and  deeper  view  of 
things  than  their  special  occupation  affords.  One  may 
find  that  the  methods  which  he  is  using  daily  become 
useless  for  certain  practical  purposes  he  has  in  view,  and 
may  thus  be  forced  to  question  the  principles  which  during 
half  his  lifetime  he  has  applied  with  unquestioning  faith 
in  their  validity  and  usefulness.  Another  may  have  met 
with  such  success  in  the  use  of  a  special  method  of  re- 
search, that  he  wishes  to  apply  it  to  subjects  which  were 
previously  handled  in  a  different  manner,  or  elevate  it  to 


64  INTRODUCTION. 

the  dignity  of  a  general  rule  of  thought.  A  third  may, 
accidentally,  be  interested  in  two  or  more  pursuits  which 
are  seemingly  unconnected,  but  which — being  brought 
side  by  side  in  his  mind — he  feels  the  wish  to  unite 
and  harmonise.  A  fourth  may,  at  a  certain  time  of  life, 
grow  tired  of  the  drudgery  of  petty  pursuits  which  neve'r 
carry  him  beyond  a  very  limited  sphere  of  interests :  he 
is  tempted  to  look  beyond  this  narrow  range,  and  gain 
some  wider  view  of  other  pursuits  and  interests.  Allowing 
that  ignorance  or  indifference  prevents  even  the  majority 
of  those  whose  powers  are  not  exhausted  in  the  struggle 
for  mere  existence  from  looking  much  beyond  their  nar- 
row circle,  allowing  also  that  many  of  us  live — like  chil- 
dren— in  a  blessed  trust  that  the  great  and  important 
interests  of  mankind  are  under  higher  and  better  guidance 
than  we  can  understand  or  control,  there  still  remain  a 
considerable  number  of  persons  who  are  always  on  the 
look-out  for  something  higher,  wider,  and  better,  who  are 
driven  by  an  undying  thirst  after  real  wisdom,  or  by  an 
9.  inherent  restlessness  of  disposition  to  inquire  into  the 

Speculation. 

deepest  foundations  and  the  ultimate  ends  of  the  world 
and  life.  Language  has  coined  a  word  which  denotes  the 
whole  of  these  occupations  and  endeavours,  how  various 
so  ever  they  may  be,  and  for  whatsoever  purpose  they  may 
be  undertaken.  It  calls  them  speculations.  The  word 
also  indicates  the  venturesome  and  risky  nature  of  these 
undertakings.  They  have  existed  in  all  ages  and  countries 
and  languages  wherever  literature  has  existed,  and  have 
been  carried  on  by  the  powers  of  reason  or  imagination, 
in  prose,  verse,  or  symbol,  sometimes  in  defined  and  clear 
terms,  more  often  in  mystic  allegory.  Philosophy  may  be 


INTRODUCTION. 


65 


said  to  have  grown  out  of  these  vague  and  scattered 
beginnings  by  the  attempt  to  conduct  them  according  to 
some  method,  and  to  unite  them  into  a  complete  and  con- 
sistent whole.  Philosophy  may  thus  be  denned  as  specula-  10. 

*       .          Philosophy 

tion  carried  on  according  to  some  clear  method,  and  aim-  defined, 
ing  at  systematic  unity.1  Both  science  and  philosophy 
may  be  called  methodical  thought,  but  the  word  system  is 
applicable  only  to  the  higher  and  more  advanced  forms  of 
philosophic  thought  which  aim  at  unity  and  completeness. 
We  have  thus  arrived  at  a  second  division  of  our  sub- 
ject. In  the  first  we  have  to  consider  thought  merely  as 
a  means  to  an  end ;  in  the  second  we  have  to  consider  it  as 
its  own  object,  as  a  reflection  on  itself,  carried  on  with  the 
object  of  knowing  its  own  origin,  its  laws,  its  validity,  of 
testing  its  powers,  and  with  the  end  and  aim  of  gaining 
certainty,  completeness,  and  unity.  The  whole  of  this  11. 

Division  of 

great  division   of   thought   I   shall   comprise   under  the  the  book. 


1  This  view  of  the  nature  and 
object  of  Philosophy  agrees  with 
Lotze'a  definition  (see  '  Grundzuge 
der  Logik,'  Leipzig,  1883,  §  88): 
"  The  common  culture  of  life  and 
the  separate  sciences  contain  a  num- 
ber of  suppositions  the  origin  of 
which  is  obscure  to  us,  because  they 
have  been  very  gradually  formed 
within  us  through  the  comparison 
of  many  experiences,  or  because 
they  have  first  become  conscious  by 
means  of  such  experiences,  have 
then  received  definite  names  and  be- 
come habitual  without  having  been 
subjected  by  us  to  any  examina- 
tion as  to  the  reason,  the  sense,  and 
the  extent  of  their  validity.  In  this 
way  science  and  life  make  use  of  the 
notions  of  cause  and  effect,  of  matter 
and  force,  of  means  and  end,  of  free- 
dom and  necessity,  of  matter  and 

VOL.  I. 


mind,  and  they  frequently  entangle 
themselves,  owing  to  the  above-men- 
tioned defect,  in  contradictions,  in- 
asmuch as  they  are  unable  to  fix  the 
limits  of  validity  of  these  to  some 
extent  contradictory  assumptions. 

"  Now  we  may  formally  define 
the  task  of  Philosophy  as  follows : 
that  it  is  an  endeavour  to  import 
unity  and  connectedness  into  the 
scattered  directions  of  cultured 
thought,  to  follow  each  of  these 
directions  into  its  assumptions  and 
into  its  consequences,  to  combine 
them  all  together,  to  remove  their 
contradictions,  and  to  form  out  of 
them  a  comprehensive  view  of  the 
world  ;  mainly,  however,  to  subject 
those  ideas  which  science  and  life 
regard  as  principles  to  a  special 
scrutiny,  in  order  to  determine  the 
limits  of  their  validity." 

E 


66 


INTRODUCTION. 


12. 

Neither 
science  nor 
philosophy 
comprises 
the  whole 
meaning  of 
the  word 
thought. 


13. 

Thought 
also  hidden 
in  the  liter- 
ature and 
art  of  the 


term  Philosophy ;  and  as  the  first  part  will  deal  with 
the  scientific,  so  will  the  second  deal  with  the  philo- 
sophical thought  of  our  century. 

Science  has  gradually  risen  out  of  the  mass  of  accu- 
mulated but  inaccurate  and  disorderly  knowledge  by 
the  desire  of  making  it  accurate,  orderly,  and  useful. 
Philosophy  has  similarly  emerged  from  the  great  world 
of  speculative  thought  by  the  desire  of  carrying  it 
on  methodically  and  for  a  defined  end  and  purpose. 
Nevertheless  neither  the  one  nor  the  other,  nor  both 
together,  really  exhaust  the  whole  meaning  of  the  word 
"  Thought " ;  neither  science  nor  philosophy  covers  the 
whole  region  of  thought.  Both  are  comprised  under  the 
term  methodical  thought;  but  there  remains  the  great 
body  of  immethodical,  undefined  thought.  This  is  buried 
in  general  literature,  in  poetry,  fiction,  and  art ;  it  shows 
its  practical  influence  in  the  artistic,  moral,  and  religions 
life  of  our  age.  It  is  a  reflection  of  the  knowledge  of 
science  or  the  light  of  philosophy,  but,  like  all  reflected 
light,  it  not  only  follows,  it  also  precedes  the  real  and  full 
light :  it  is  not  only  the  dusk  that  comes  after,  it  is  also 
the  dawn  that  comes  before  the  day,  it  is  the  twilight 
of  thought.  In  it  lie  hidden  the  germs  of  future  thought, 
the  undeveloped  beginnings  of  art,  philosophy,  and  science 
yet  unknown  and  undreamt  of ;  it  encloses  and  surrounds 
the  innermost  recesses  of  the  mind,  where  all  thought  had 
its  origin,  and  whence  it  ever  and  again  draws  fresh  life 
and  inspiration.1 


1  This  is  originally  a  Leibnizian 
idea.  It  is  laid  down  in  the  doctrine 
of  the  petites  perceptions,  as  given 


in  the  introduction  to  the  '  Nou- 
veaux  Essais,'  and  referred  to  in 
many  passages  of  Leibniz's  various 


INTRODUCTION.  67 

No  account  of  the  thought  of  our  century  would  be 
complete  or  satisfactory  which  took  no  notice  of  this  great 
volume  of  unmethodical  and  unsystematic  thought  which 
lies  buried  in  the  general  literature  and  in  the  art  of 
the  age.  Both  have  shown  a  vitality,  originality,  and 
versatility  which  exceed  that  of  any  except  the  few 
favoured  periods — those  of  Athens  under  Pericles,  Italy 
during  the  Renaissance,  and  England  under  Elizabeth. 
In  one  of  the  arts,  in  music,  our  age  has,  according  to  the 
opinion  of  many  competent  judges,  exceeded  in  originality 
and  certainly  in  productiveness  all  former  ages.  In 
poetry  Goethe  and  Wordsworth  have  raised  our  tastes  H. 

Goethe  and 

and  demands  to   a  higher  level,  in  fiction  France  and  Wordsworth 

raised  our 

England  have  almost  created  a  new  branch  of  literature,  tastes* 
whilst  the  peculiar  features  of  modern  English  landscape- 
painting  were  unknown  to  previous  centuries.     All  this, 
though  produced  under  no  scientific  or  philosophical  rule 


writings.  See  'Nouv.  Ess.,'  Pre-  pourraient  lire  toute  la  suite  des 
face,  Leibniz,  Philosophische  Werke,  choses  de  1'univers. 
ed.  Gerhardt,  vol.  v.  p.  48  : —  "  Qua)  sint,  qua;  fuerint,  qua) 
"Cespetites  perceptions  sontdonc  mox  futura  trahantur.  .  .  .  C'est 
de  plus  grandeefficace par  leur  suites  aussi  par  les  perceptions  insensibles 
qu'on  ne  pense.  Ce  sont  elles  qui  que  s'explique  cette  admirable  har- 
fornient  oe  je  ne  8£ay  quoy,  ces  monie  preestablie  de  1'ame  et  du 
gouts,  ees  images  des  qualitds  des  corps,  et  meme  de  toutes  les  Mon- 
sens,  claires  dans  I'assemblage,  mais  ades  ou  substances  simples,  qui  sup- 
confuses  dans  les  parties,  ces  im-  plee  a  1'influence  insoiitenable  des 
pressions  que  des  corps  environnans  uns  sur  les  autres,  et  qui  au  juge- 
font  sur  nous,  qui  envelopperit  incut  de  1'auteur  du  plus  beau  des 
1'infiui,  cette  liaison  que  chaque  j  Dictionnaires  exalte  la  grandeur 
estre  a  avec  tout  le  reste  de  1'uni-  des  perfections  divines  au  dela  de 
vers.  On  peut  meme  dire  qu'eu  ce  qu'on  eu  jamais  coucu." 
consequence  de  ces  petites  percep-  |  The  importance  of  this  idea  of 
tions  le  present  est  gros  de  1'avenir  Leibniz  has  been  dwelt  on  at  length 
et  chargd  du  passe,  que  tout  est  by  Kuno  Fischer  in  his  '  Geschichte 
conspirant  (a-vfjurvota  ireCvTo,  comme  der  neueren  Philosophic,"  where  he 
disoit  Hippocrate)  et  que  dans  la  also  traces  its  influence  in  the 
moindre  des  substances,  des  yeux  development  of  philosophy  and 
AUSSI  percans  qu«  «eux  de  Dieu  I  literature  in  Germany  after  Leibniz. 


68  INTRODUCTION. 

and  very  frequently  outside  of  any  school,  points  to  novel 
modes  of  mental  conception,  to  a  fund  of  ideas  yet  un- 
developed or  only  partially  developed  into  clear  thought. 
The  whole  of  this  productiveness  indicates  a  vast  amount 
of  mental  work  which,  though  not  yet  absorbed  by  science 
or  philosophy,  belongs  nevertheless,  according  to  our 
original  conception,  to  the  world  of  thought.  The  mean- 
ing of  it  may  be  enigmatical,  and  the  clear  expression 
which  it  will  some  day  produce  in  philosophical  and 
scientific  reasoning  may  be  far  distant  and  unintelligible 
15.  to  us  now.  Still  there  it  is,  this  great  body  of  undefined 

Unmethodi- 
cal thought,  thought,    this    volume    of    diffused   light,    the    focus  and 

centre  of  which  is  still  hidden  from  us.  We  feel  that  in 
discussing  the  thought  of  the  century  we  cannot  pass  it 
by  or  neglect  it. 

It  is  difficult  to  find  any  one  term  under  which  we 
could  comprise  this  great  body  of  unmethodical,  scattered, 
and  fragmentary  thought, — any  one  word,  similar  to 
science  and  philosophy,  in  which  we  could  sum  up  and 
characterise  its  general  meaning  and  tendency.  So  far 
we  have  only  stated  what  it  is  not,  what  to  a  large  extent 
it  perhaps  never  will  be — viz.,  methodical.  And  yet  we 
feel  that  it  contains  that  kind  and  portion  of  thought 
which  touches  our  deepest  interests,  our  most  intimate 
concerns,  our  noblest  aspirations.  Science  becomes  more 
and  more  a  mere  calculation,  une  question  d'analyse,  an 
occupation  for  the  laboratory,  the  workshop,  the  manu- 
factory, and  the  market ;  philosophy  savours  at  its  best 
too  much  of  the  school  and  lecture-room,  runs  too  much 
into  systems  and  categories,  it  fatigues  us  with  definitions 


INTRODUCTION.  69 

and  abstractions.     But  neither  calculation  and  measure-        ie. 

Summed 

ment,  nor  definition  and  abstraction,  suffice  to  exhaust  up iu  the 

term  reli- 

what  is  to  us,  in  the  quiet  and  serious  moments  of  life,  of  ^*ffht 
the  deepest  concern — viz.,  our  religion.  I  use  the  word 
here  in  its  original  sense,  and  I  propose  to  sum  up  in  the 
term  religious  thought  the  whole  of  the  thought  contained 
in  that  large  volume  of  literature  which  does  not  submit 
to  scientific  and  philosophical  treatment,  but  which  never- 
theless forms  so  important  an  outcome  of  the  mental  life 
of  the  century. 

There  are  other  words  more  or  less  current  in  modern 
literature  that  may  serve  to  throw  some  light  on  the 
distinction  that  I  am  here  drawing  for  the  purpose  of 
affording  a  preliminary  view  of  the  course  to  be  pur- 
sued in  the  following  treatise. 

Science  is  said  to  be  exact,  positive,  and  objective,  and       17. 

Science  is 

it  is  opposed  to  such  other  thought  as  is  inexact,  vague,  exact,  posi 

tive,  and 

and  subjective.  Science  is  said  to  convey  its  results  or  objective, 
ideas  in  defined,  direct,  and  general  terms,  whereas  there 
is  a  large  department  of  literature  and  thought  which 
moves  in  undefined,  symbolical,  and  indirect  expressions. 
Science  professes  to  rest  on  clear  and  precise  knowledge, 
and  is  thus  opposed  to  such  other  realms  of  thought  as 
rest  on  opinion,  belief,  and  faith.  It  may  be  well  to  note 
here  that  these  different  terms  refer  either  to  the  method 
of  treatment  or  to  the  matter  which  is  under  treatment. 
Science  alone  professes  to  have  a  rigid  and  undisputed 
method.  Other  branches  of  thought  either  borrow  their 
methods  from  science,  or  they  have  fluctuating,  not  gener- 
ally recognised  methods,  or  they  refuse  to  submit  to  method 


70  INTRODUCTION. 

altogether.  But  so  far  as  the  matter  under  treatment  is 
concerned,  a  clearer  division  is  possible.  Science  deals 
with  all  such  things  or  objects  of  thought  as  are  common 
to  a  great  many  persons  and — under  certain  circumstances 
— are  accessible  to  everybody  :  it  thus  claims  that  its  ob- 
servations and  reasonings  can  be  checked  and  submitted  to 
repeated  examination  and  verification  ;  so  that  a  large  por- 
tion of  them  can  always  be  regarded  as  settled  and  agreed 
upon,  and  can  be  taken  for  granted  and  used  as  a  secure 
foundation  by  those  persons  who  are  themselves  unable  or 
•  unwilling  to  go  through  the  process  of  verification.  But 
is.  there  are  a  great  many  things  and  interests  which  centre 
terests  or  in  the  individual  mind  of  each  person — which  are,  in  fact, 

objects  of 

thrsonaiaor    Personal>  individual,  or  subjective.     They  are  to  all  of  us 
subjective.    jusj.  ag  imp0rtant  as  the  others.     They  form  the  real  sub- 
ject-matter of  all  that  thought  which  is  separated  from 
science,  and  in  its  very  nature  and  aspect  opposed  to  it. 
In  this  great  province  of  thought  one  person  cannot  do 
the  work  for  many  in  the  same  way  as  is  possible  in 
19.        science.     Proof  is  almost  impossible,  and  agreement  refers 

Agreement 

on  these       always  only  to  a  certain  number  of  persons.     Doctrines  or 

matters 

impossible,  theories  in  this  region  of  thought  cannot  be  accepted  and 
taken  for  granted  as  they  are  in  science,  but  every  person 
must  go  over  the  same  ground  for  himself  before  he  has 
any  right  to  accept  or  make  use  of  what  is  given  to  him. 
The  real  and  true  character  of  all  this  thought  is  that  it 
is  individual  and  personal,  whereas  all  scientific  thought 
— whatever  its  origin  may  be — must  be  general  and  im- 
personal. At  the  extreme  end  of  thought  in  one  direction 
are  placed  the  mathematical  sciences,  at  the  extreme  end 
in  the  other  lies  religion.  Disagreement  in  the  former  is 


INTRODUCTION. 


71 


almost  as  unknown l  as  agreement  in  the  latter.  There 
we  have  an  almost  universal  unity  of  thought ;  here  unity 
of  thought  probably  never  existed ;  it  is  unknown.  Popu- 
larly we  can  say  that  at  the  one  extreme  lie  knowledge 
and  certainty,  at  the  other  faith  and  belief.  There  is, 
however,  a  very  large  extent  of  ground  between  these  two 
extremes.  This  is  covered  by  all  such  intermediate  thought 
as  rests  partly  on  knowledge,  partly  on  faith,  where  cer- 
tainty is  largely  mingled  with  belief.  This  large  inter-  20. 

'     J  Philosophy 

mediate  region,  where  changes  and  fluctuations  are  fre-  intermedi- 
ate between 

quent  and  rapid,  is  the  proper  home  of  philosophy,  which  "f^™^" 
occupies  itself  with  the  grounds  of  certainty  and  belief,  and  religion' 
the  origin  of  knowledge  and  faith,  and  the  relations  in 
which  both  stand  to  each  other.  Were  all  our  thoughts 
either  purely  mathematical  —  i.e.,  referring  to  number, 
measurement,  and  calculation,  or  purely  religious — i.e., 
referring  to  our  individual  concerns  and  personal  convic- 
tions,— the  need  of  a  continued  compromise  or  mediation 
would  be  unnecessary,  the  question  as  to  the  grounds  of 
certainty  or  belief  would  never  arise.  But  no  sooner 
do  we  wish  either  to  apply  our  strict  mathematical  no- 
tions and  processes,  or  to  bring  our  personal  convictions 
into  practical  use,  than  the  two  kinds  of  thought  come 
into  contact,  not  to  say  into  conflict,  and  there  is  need 
of  some  theory  according  to  which  this  contact  may  be 
regulated,  this  conflict  settled.  And  as  the  occasions  for 
such  contact  change  with  the  demands  of  practical  life,  or 


1  It  may  be  doubted  whether  this 
is  quite  correct,  looking  at  the  con- 
troversies which  have  been  connec- 
ted with  many  mathematical  theo- 
ries— such  as  the  theory  of  parallel 
Hues,  the  meaning  of  infinitesimals, 


the  correct  measure  of  force. 
These  controversies,  however,  re- 
ferred really  to  applied,  not  to  pure 
mathematics,  and  were  settled  by 
introducing  corrector  and  more 
stringent  definitions. 


72 


INTRODUCTION. 


21. 

Threefold 
considera- 
tion of 
thought : 
scientific, 
philosophi- 
cal, indi- 
vidual. 


the  progress  of  applied  science,  these  theories  must  them- 
selves change  and  develop.  Now  it  may  be  generally 
stated  that  it  is  the  task  of  philosophy  to  take  note  of 
these  different  ways  by  which  the  strict  methods  of  science 
are  applied  and  made  useful,  or  by  which  personal  and 
individual  convictions  are  brought  to  bear  upon  practical 
questions  which  are  not  only  of  personal  but  of  general  in- 
terest and  importance.  It  does  not  follow  that  philosophy 
must  necessarily  construct  a  complete  system ;  but  it  is  a 
natural  and  frequent  occurrence  that  the  occupation  with 
a  great  number  of  detached  theories  or  aspects  of  thought 
generates  the  desire  to  bring  them  into  harmony  and  to 
unite  them  in  a  connected  whole.  Thus  the  enterprise 
which  was  originally  purely  critical  and  preparatory,  and 
undertaken  merely  as  a  means  to  an  end,  may  lead  to  the 
formation  of  a  general  and  all-embracing  view  of  things 
— i.e.,  to  a  philosophical  system. 

From  whichever  side  we  approach  the  matter,  we  are 
thus  always  led  to  a  threefold  consideration  of  thought, 
as  scientific,  as  individual,  and  as  philosophical.  An  at- 
tempt in  which  any  of  these  three  aspects  were  neglected 
could  have  no  value  in  an  account  of  the  thought  of  our 
age.  There  have  indeed  been  schools  of  thought  which 
identified  science  with  philosophy,  or  which  maintained 
that  no  independence  belonged  to  religious,  personal,  or 
individual  thought,  inasmuch  as  this  was  merely  of  a 
derived  character.  Though  such  theories  may  have  ex- 
erted considerable  influence,  they  have  as  a  whole  failed,1 

1  This  can  be  said  of  Hegelian-  art.  See  Hegel,  '  Geschichte  der 
ism  as  well  as  of  Com tism.  In  the  Philosophic '  (Werke.  vol.  xv.  p. 
former  it  was  a  favourite  doctrine  684) :  "  The  highest  aim  and  inter- 
that  philosophy  was  the  higher  est  of  philosophy  is  to  reconcile 
wisdom  compared  with  religion  and  thought,  the  idea,  with  reality. 


INTRODUCTION.  73 

p 

and  we  find  ourselves  at  the  end  of  a  long  and  critical 
period  unable  to  say  that  any  one  of  the  three  realms 
of  thought  has  gained  an  undisputed  victory  over  the 
others.  Science  is  more  than  ever  that  kind  of  thought 
which  gives  knowledge  and  certainty.  Eeligion  is  still 
the  generally  recognised  abode  for  those  convictions 
which  refer  to  our  deepest  personal  interests.  And  more 
than  ever  do  we  feel  the  need  of  a  reconciliation  of  both  22. 

Philosophy 

in  some  theory  of  life  which  is  neither  purely  scientific  nor  «ie  media- 

<t  »  tor  between 

purely  individualistic ;  and  this  means  that  philosophy  is 
as  much  needed  as  ever.  Our  century  has  witnessed  a 
great  development  of  scientific  thought,  a  great  revival  in 
religious  interest,  religious  feeling,  and  religious  activity, 
and  it  is  probably  richer  than  any  preceding  age  in 
philosophical  theories  and  systems. 

I  must  repeat  here  what  I  said  above,  that  it  is  a 
misfortune  that  in  dealing  with  a  complicated  subject 
we  are  obliged  to  divide  it, — that  we  are  forced  to  give 
preference  to  some  one  aspect,  and  to  choose  a  special 

Philosophy  is  the  veritable  theo-  gious  belief,  which  threatened  to  be 
dicy,  compared  with  art  and  religion  lost  in  the  rationalistic  and  mystical 
and  their  sentiments — this  recon-  schools  of  the  day.  And  this  had 
ciliation  of  the  mind,  indeed  of  that  the  further  consequence  that  a 
mind  which  has  grasped  itself  in  the  scientific  occupation  with  or  inter- 
freedom  and  wealth  of  its  reality.  est  in  religious  subjects — be  it  meta- 
It  is  easy  otherwise  to  find  satisfac-  physical  or  historical — took  the 
tion  in  subordinate  regions  of  intui-  place  of  a  purely  religious  interest, 
tion  and  feeling,"  &c.,  &c.  Al-  j  and  that  many  eminent  German 
though  it  is  an  exaggeration  to  say  theologians  became  either  pure 
that  Hegel  desired  to  absorb  or  metaphysicians  or  merely  critics, 
evaporate  religious  belief  in  philo-  the  practical  side  being  lost  sight  of. 
sophical  knowledge,  as  his  lengthy  It  is  probably  just  as  incorrect 
explanation  (Introduction  to  the  to  accuse  Comte  of  an  intention 
'  History  of  Philosophy,'  Works,  vol.  to  destroy  true  religion  because  he 
xiii.  p.  77  sqq.)  sufficiently  proves,  preached  the  well-known  doctrine 
there  is  no  doubt  that  the  senti-  of  the  three  stages  of  human 
ment  expressed  in  the  above  pas-  thought — the  theological,  the  meta- 
sage  indicates  that  philosophy  was  physical,  and  the  scientific  or  posi- 
coming  to  the  rescue  of  true  reli-  tive. 


74  INTRODUCTION. 

point  from  which  to  set  out.  In  dealing  with  the 
thought  of  our  age,  I  have  been  obliged  to  divide  what 
is  in  reality  connected  and  coherent ;  and  I  ana  further 
forced,  in  examining  more  closely  its  different  aspects, 
to  select  one  as  the  most  prominent  with  which  to  make 
a  beginning.  In  reality  such  a  preference  does  not  exist 
in  my  plan.  I  recognise  all  the  aspects  of  thought  as 
equally  important,  and  I  feel  that  I  might  begin  with 
any  one  of  the  three,  and  that  I  should  in  due  course  be 
23.  led  on  to  a  consideration  of  the  other  two.  They  are  in 

Difficult  to 

separate  the  their  actual  historical  appearance  in  the  course  of  our  period 
thought.  so  interwoven  that  they  cannot  practically  be  separated. 
And  it  is  indeed  not  difficult  to  assume  various  positions 
in  contemplating  the  whole  subject  from  which  either  one 
or  the  other  of  the  three  forms  of  nineteenth-century 
thought  assumes  as  it  were  the  ascendancy.  Thus  it 
would  be  undeniable  that  from  a  German  point  of  view 
the  great  movement  of  ideas  centred  in  the  first  third  of 
the  century  in  what  I  have  called  philosophy.  The 
number  of  systems  which  succeeded  each  other  was 
astonishing,  the  influence  they  had  on  literature,  science, 
and  practical  life  was  without  precedent,  the  enthusi- 
asm with  which  students  from  all  parts  gathered  in  the 
lecture-rooms  of  the  great  metaphysicians  was  quite 
extraordinary,  and  probably  equalled  only  in  the  schools 
of  Athens  in  antiquity,  or  in  the  lecture-room  of  Abelard 
in  the  middle  ages.  From  this  point  of  view  an  account 
of  this  great  movement — how  it  grew,  flourished,  and 
died  away — would  no  doubt  afford  a  suitable  introduc- 
tion to  the  history  of  thought  in  our  century.  If  after 
this  we  were  to  turn  to  France  and  try  to  fix  upon  the 


INTRODUCTION.  75 

most  striking  intellectual  feature  of  the  century,  it  would        24. 

French 

be  the  equally  great  and  remarkable  array  of  scientific  ^""^t^ 
names  of  the  first  magnitude.  In  France  during  the  ,?nge?he  tint 
early  part  of  the  century  the  foundation  of  nearly  all  the  century.  e 
modern  sciences  was  laid ;  many  of  them  were  brought 
under  the  rule  of  a  strict  mathematical  treatment.  It 
was  there  that  scientific  subjects  were  made  so  popular, 
and  clothed  with  a  garment  of  such  elegant  diction,  that 
they  have  since  that  time  greatly  entered  into  general 
consciousness,  and  have  promoted  in  literature  and  art 
an  independent  school  —  the  naturalistic.  Compared 
with  this  mathematical  and  naturalistic  spirit,  philo- 
sophy proper  has  found  but  a  meagre  development  and 
culture  in  France :  the  constructive  tendency  of  ideal- 
ism has  found  nourishment  for  the  most  part  only  in 
leanings  to  the  older  systems  of  Descartes,  Plato,  and 
Aristotle,  or  to  the  foreign  ones  of  Hegel  and  other 
German  metaphysicians.  Compared  with  Germany  in 
philosophy,  and  with  France  in  science,  England  during 
the  early  part  of  the  century  appears  remarkably  unpro- 
ductive. English  science  and  English  philosophy  had 
flourished  in  the  seventeenth  and  eighteenth  centuries, 
and  leavened  the  whole  of  European  thought,  but  in  the 
beginning  of  our  period  we  find  neither  represented  by 
any  great  schools.  The  great  discoveries  in  science  be- 
longed to  individual  names,  who  frequently  stood  iso- 
lated ;  the  organisation  and  protection  which  science  could 
boast  of  in  France  was  then  unknown  in  England ;  into  State25j 
popular  thought  it  hardly  entered  as  an  element  at  all.  fnhtl?e 
Metaphysics  had  not  recovered  from  the  blow  which  nfn 
David  Hume  had  struck,  and  speculation  was  confined 


76  INTRODUCTION. 

almost  entirely  to  the  novel  field  of  social  and  economic 
problems.  But  against  this  there  was  a  young  growth 
of  ideas  springing  up  in  the  poetic  literature  of  the 
nation.  It  is  the  freshness  of  individual  thought  as 
clothed  in  the  poetic  language  of  Shelley  and  Words- 
worth, maturing  and  deepening  in  the  works  of  Tennyson 
and  Browning,  which  strikes  us  as  the  most  original  phase 
of  English  thought  in  this  century,  whether  we  compare 
it  with  Continental  thought  of  the  same  period,  or  with 
English  thought  of  the  previous  age. 
26.  And  lastly,  we  might  be  tempted  to  make  the  great 

Goethe's 


work  of  the  greatest  mind  of  the  early  part  of  our  period, 
Goethe's  '  Faust,'  the  centre  and  beginning  of  our  survey, 
tury-  singling  it  out  as  a  comprehensive  embodiment,  as  the 
classical  expression  of  nineteenth  -  century  doubts  and 
aspirations,  leading  us  —  if  we  try  to  understand  it  — 
now  into  the  bewildering  labyrinth  of  philosophy,  now 
into  the  cheerful  expanse  of  natural  science,  and  again 
into  the  hidden  depths  of  individual  life,  of  religious 
faith  with  its  mysteries  of  sin  and  redemption. 

But  from  whatsoever  point  we  may  start  on  our  journey, 

from  whatsoever  easily  reached  eminence  we  may  cast  a 

first  eager  glance  across  the  wide  country  which  we  wish 

to  explore,  there  is  one  feature  which   impresses   itself 

27.        alike  upon  our  minds  from  the  very  beginning.      It  is  not 

otofre-      a  country  of  repose  and  restfulness,  of  healthy  industry 

ferment.       anc\   quiet   work,   of    gradual   development,   of    ripening 

crops,  of  sowing  or  ingathering  ;  it  does  not  present  the 

aspect  of  a  happy  division  of  labour,  of  successful  co- 

operation, of  peaceful  regulation  of  employment.     It  looks 

more   like  a  land  which   has   lately  been  disturbed  by 


INTRODUCTION.  77 

great  elemental  forces,  heaved  up  by  an  earthquake  or 
visited  by  a  destructive  storm.  We  see  some  persons  em- 
ployed in  filling  up  great  breaches  and  recently  made  rents, 
others  trying  to  lay  new  foundations  ;  others  again  are 
fighting  for  their  possession  or  trying  to  divide  a  disputed 
territory  ;  even  the  peaceful  workers  are  called  out  to  help 
in  the  battle,  or  disturbed  by  the  complaints  of  their 
neighbours,  on  whose  ground  they  are  trespassing  un- 
awares, whose  foundations  they  are  unconsciously  under- 
mining. If  we  inquire  into  the  cause  of  this  unrest  and  28. 

Cause  of  it 

anxiety,  which  seems  to  be  a  feature  common  to  nearly  seen  in  the 

J    century  of 

all  the  phases  of  nineteenth-century  thought,  we  must  ^ed^^it 
look  back  to  the  age  which  immediately  preceded  it.     It 
is  the  storm  of  the  revolution  which  passed  over  Europe, 
and  shook  to  the  foundation  all  political  and  social  in- 
stitutions, that  has  likewise  affected  our  ideas  and  thoughts 
in  every  direction.     The  period  we  refer  to  has  thus  not 
incorrectly  been  termed  a  century  of  revolution.      If  in        29. 
spite  of   this  I  decline   to   consider  nineteenth  -century  century 

thought 

thought  as  essentially  revolutionary,  it  is  because  the  aotiwota. 
work  of  destruction  belongs  in  its  earlier  and  more 
drastic  episodes  to  the  preceding  age.  The  beginning 
of  our  period  witnesses  everywhere  the  desire  to  recon- 
struct, either  by  laying  new  foundations  or  by  reverting 
to  older  forms  of  thought  and  life  which  it  tries  to 
support  by  new  arguments  or  to  enliven  by  a  fresh  in- 
terest and  meaning.  We  may  say  that  the  thought  of  so. 

Thought  of 

the  century  in  its  practical   bearings  is  partly  radical, 


partly   reactionary,  —  meaning   by  the   former   all   those 
constructive   attempts  which  try  to  go   to   the   root  of  ary' 
things  and  to  build  up  on  newly  prepared  ground;  by 


78  INTRODUCTION. 

the  latter  all  those  endeavours  which,  clinging  to  his- 
torical institutions  and  beliefs,  aim  at  finding  the  truth 
and  value  which  are  in  them,  and  the  peculiar  importance 
which  they  may  have  for  the  present  day.     The  work  of 
destruction  is  indeed  still  going  on ;  in  the  midst  of  this 
constructive  or  reconstructive  work  we  still  witness  the 
si.        workings  of  the  revolutionary  spirit.     The  healthy  new 
of  Burns,      Hfe  which  Burns,  Wordsworth,  and  Coleridge  infused  into 
coieri'd^d    English  poetry  at  the  beginning  of  our  period  was  dis- 
thetBryraiic'  turbed  in  its  quiet  growth  by  the  revolutionary  spirit  of 
the  Byronic  school.     The  new  thought,  which  grew  up  in 
Kant's  philosophy  and  the  idealistic  school,  degenerated  in 
its  further  development  into  a  shallow  materialism  and 
a  hopeless  scepticism.     But  none  of  these  destructive  in- 
fluences, however  passingly  interesting   they  may  have 
been,  seem  to  have  struck  out  any  new  line  of  thought. 
32.        Whoever  wishes  to  study  the  arguments  by  which  social 

Destructive 

spirit  in       order  was  svibverted  and  cherished  beliefs  destroyed  will 

writings  of 

find  them  brilliantly  and  consistently  expounded  in  the 
writers  of  the  eighteenth  century,  from  which  many 
nihilists  of  our  age  have  drawn  their  inspiration.  This 
is  not  the  task  which  I  have  in  view.  It  has  been  per- 
formed in  our  time  by  many  writers  of  great  eminence. 
Nor  do  I  intend  to  describe  the  courses  which  governments 
and  politicians  have  taken  in  dealing  with  the  legitimate 
demands  of  the  people,  such  as  a  hundred  years  ago  found 
a  memorable  expression  in  the  American  Declaration  of 
Independence,  and  an  exaggerated  one  in  the  cry  of  the 
French  Revolution.  Only  to  a  small  extent  has  the  ideal 
of  that  great  movement,  as  it  lives  in  the  mind  of  many 
a  democratic  leader,  been  realised  in  our  century.  In 


INTRODUCTION.  79 

most  European  countries  the  work  of  national  unification 
and  consolidation,  and  the  struggle  for  political  indepen- 
dence, have  retarded  internal  reforms  ;  nor  have  theorists 
been  able  to  agree  in  what  form  of  social  organisation 
liberty  and  equality  could  consistently  live  side  by  side. 
Their  teaching  must  indeed  command  special  attention  33. 

Revolution- 

as  one  of  the  many  forms  of  the  philosophic  thought  of  ary  theories 

not  practi- 

the  age ;  but  a  wide  gap  separates  theory  from  practical  cal- 
politics,  which  have  been  largely  occupied  with  wars  and 
diplomatic  feats,  or, when  they  really  dealt  with  social  prob- 
lems, have  had  to  be  content  with  awkward  compromises 
between  prejudices  and  institutions  of  bygone  ages  on  the 
one  side,  and  legitimate  demands  for  freedom  on  the  other. 
Though  much  practical  thought  and  much  labour  have 
been  spent  in  achieving  even  these  moderate  results,  I  feel 
that  they  really  fall  outside  of  my  programme.  Wherever 
either  science  or  philosophy  steps  out  of  the  quiet  regions 
of  the  study,  the  lecture- room,  and  the  laboratory,  or 
wherever  religious  faith  leaves  the  secret  recesses  of  the 
believing  soul  to  solve  the  problems  of  life  or  to  perform 
the  work  of  the  day,  the  line  is  crossed  which  I  have  felt 
obliged  to  draw  around  the  following  sketch.  Not  that  I 
do  not  recognise  this  borderland,  where  the  spirit  subdues 
matter,  where  thought  becomes  useful,  where  the  idea 
attains  reality,  this  field  of  strife  and  endeavour,  of  patient 
toil  and  slow  victory,  as  by  far  the  most  important  subject 
of  history,  and  as  that  in  which  our  age  has  probably  ex- 
celled every  earlier  period.  But  an  account  of  this  side  of 
nineteenth-century  life  could  ill  afford  to  limit  its  view  to 
the  three  principal  countries  of  the  Old  World.  For  where 
are  discovery  and  invention  at  this  moment  more  at  home 


80  INTRODUCTION. 

than  in  America;  where  have  political  theories,  the  original 
rights  of  man,  the  ideas  of  liberty,  equality,  and  brother- 
hood, been  more  widely  put  to  the  test ;  where  have  reli- 
gious beliefs  entered  into  closer  contact  with  the  work  of 
the  day ;  or  where  in  our  age  has  the  simple  rule  of  early 
Christianity  been  more  successfully  put  into  practice  ? 
An  account  of  the  application  of  thought  taken  merely 
from  our  European  experience,  where  half  our  endeavour 
must  always  be  spent  in  clearing  away  obstacles,  in 
removing  the  debris  of  antiquated  institutions,  in  over- 
coming prejudice,  or  battling  with  evils  which  have  grown 
to  uncontrollable  magnitude,  would  give  us  but  a  poor 
notion  of  the  influence  of  thought  over  material  circum- 
stances, and  a  very  exaggerated  one  of  the  inertia  of  the 
34.  mechanism  of  older  societies.  With  the  work  of  the  in- 

This  is  not 

a  history  of  ventor,  the  practical  statesman,  or  the  lawgiver,  I  have  thus 

invention 

cai°popimcs'"  notning  to  do  at  present;  only  in  cases  where  practical 
problems  have  immediately  reacted  upon  scientific  research, 
or  where  social  questions  have  given  rise  to  special  theo- 
ries, shall  we  be  compelled  to  cast  a  glance  outside  of  the 
inner  world  of  thought  into  which  I  invite  my  readers  to 
retire. 

This  inner  world  has,  indeed,  not  been  all  rest  and  peace 
and  quiet  development.  No  age  has  been  so  rich  in  rival 
theories,  so  subversive  of  old  ideas,  so  destructive  of  prin- 
ciples which  stood  firm  for  many  ages,  as  ours.  It  is  not 
my  intention  to  emphasise  this  critical  or  radical  tendency 

35. 

be  co^sid*-0  niore  than  is  necessary.  True  to  the  original  view  which  I 
contra!?  have  already  expressed,  I  intend  to  look  upon  thought  as 
tatted*  a  constructive,  not  a  destructive  agency ;  on  the  world  of 

structive 

attitude.       ideas  as  a  positive  acquisition,  not  as  a  mere  counterpart 


INTRODUCTION.  81 

or  shadow  of  material  existence.  Though  demanding  for 
its  growth  an  outer  stimulus,  and  unable  to  proceed  very 
far  without  external  correctives,  I  nevertheless  maintain 
that  the  human  mind  in  its  individual  and  collective  life 
encloses  an  independent  source  of  reality  which  contact 
with  outer  things  and  thought  in  all  its  various  forms 
has  to  reveal,  to  preserve,  and  to  develop.  To  what 
extent  this  has  been  done  in  our  century  is  the  question 
I  propose  to  answer.  "With  this  object  in  view  I  shall 
try  to  gather  my  observations  and  my  narrative  around 
the  prominent  and  novel  constructive  ideas  which  have 
sprung  up  in  the  course  of  the  century,  not  omitting 
the  great  development  which  the  purely  formal  side  of 
thought,  the  method  of  research,  has  undergone.  Such 
constructive  ideas  are  those  of  energy,  its  conservation 
and  dissipation ;  the  doctrine  of  averages,  statistics,  and 
probabilities ;  Darwin's  and  Spencer's  ideas  of  evolution  ze. 
in  science  and  philosophy ;  the  doctrines  of  individualism  spencer's, 

and  Lotze's 

and  personality,  and  Lotze's  peculiar  view  of  the  world  ^°asstructive 
of  "values"  or  "worths."    Around  these  centres  of  thought 
cluster  the  many  critical  oppositions,  the  great  contro- 
versies of  radical  or  conservative  opponents.     As  regards 
these,  I  shall  welcome  all  radicalism  which  lays  bare  the        37. 
roots  of  our  ideas,  which  delves  deep  into  the  ground  sort  o'fradi- 

.  calism. 

of  our  opinions  and  principles,  or  which  points  out  new 
methods  by  which  we  may  test  the  correctness  and  con- 
sistency of  our  axioms.  As  such  I  consider  the  spirit 
infused  by  Kant  into  all  modern  thought.  That  other 
radicalism,  which  merely  roots  up,  which  destroys  with- 
out building,  which  fails  to  find  any  ground  of  certainty, 
simply  because  human  thought  and  observation  may  after 
VOL.  i.  F 


82  INTRODUCTION. 

all  be  a  delusion, — this  kind  of  radicalism  I  shall  try  to 
pass  over  as  meaningless.  And  equally  meaningless 
appear  to  me  those  opposite  conservative  tendencies 
which  merely  annul  progress,  which  shut  out  the  day- 
light, and  preach  the  doctrine  of  inertia.  But  this,  again, 
will  not  prevent  me  from  recognising  the  real  gain  and 
ss.  interest  which  belong  to  some  reactionary  movements. 

Reactionary 

movement     such  as  lay  at  the  bottom  of  Eonaanticism,  with  its  love 

of  Romanti- 

of  the  past,  its  artistic  idealisation  of  the  childhood  of 
mankind,  of  aspects  of  life  in  their  infancy  and  primitive- 
ness,  with  its  study  of  medievalism  and  its  more  sober 
historical  tastes.  I  shall  endeavour  always  to -ask  what 
addition  to  the  great  stock  of  human  ideas  has  resulted  ; 
what  gain  we  have  to  register ;  convinced  that  every- 
thing that  lives  must  grow,  increase,  and  multiply :  and 
what  can  be  more  living  than  Thought  ? 

But  although  the  school  of  Critical  Thought  in  Kant, 
and  the  Eomantic  school  as  centred  in  "Walter  Scott  and 
the  German  Romanticists,  are  in  time  almost  the  first 
intellectual  phases  of  the  century,  they  will  not  in  the 
beginning  command  my  special  attention.1 

1  In  order  to  give  some  idea  of  the  complexity  of  the  different  currents 
of  thought  in  the  first  years  of  the  century,  I  place  here  a  carefully 
selected  list  of  dates.  They  refer  to  events  or  publications  which  mark 
epochs  or  important  stages  in  the  history  of  thought.  Of  specifically 
scientific  importance  are — 

1796.  Laplace's  'Exposition  du  Syateme  du  Monde.' 

1799.  (2  vols.) — 1825.     Laplace's  '  Mecanique  celeste.' 

1799.  Legendre's  'Theorie  des  Xombres.' 

1801.  Gauss's  '  Disquisitiones  Arithmetics. ' 

1801.  Piazzi  discovers  and 

1802  Olbers  rediscovers  the  first  of  the  minor  planets,  "Ceres,"  being 
assisted  by  Gauss's  new  methods  of  calculation,  which  were 
published  in  extenso  in 

1809.  Gauss's  'Theoria  motus  corporum  ccelestium.' 

1798.  Cuvier's  'Tableau  elementaire  d'Histoire  uaturelle.' 

1800-5.  Cuvier's  '  Lecons  d' Anatomic  comparee. ' 


INTRODUCTION.  83 

Though  somewhat  later  in  point  of  time  than  they,  the 
school  of  exact  research  seems  to  have  become  the  more 
generally  recognised  agent  in  nineteenth-century  progress. 

1809.  Lamarck's  'Philosophic  zoologique.' 

1799.  Volta  constructs  his  first  electric  pile,  and  announces  this  in 

1800  to  Sir  Joseph  Banks. 

In  chemistry  the  early  years  of  the  century  brought  many  of  Gay- 
Lussac's  important  Memoirs,  in 

1801  Humphry  Davy  publishes  the  first  of  his  electro-chemical  dis- 

coveries, and 

1802-3  Berzelius  publishes  his  own. 
1803.  Berthollet's  'Essai  de  Statique  chimique.' 

1810.  John  Dalton's  '  New  System  of  Chemical  Philosophy.' 

1801.  Thomas  Young  announces  to  the  Royal  Society  his  belief  in  the 

undulatory  theory  of  light,  which  during 

1802,  3,  and  4  he  substantiates  further  in  his  papers,  and  fully  expounds 

during 

1802  and  following  years  in  his  lectures  to  the  Royal  Institution. 
1808.  Malus  announces  his  discovery  of  the  polarisation  of  light  through 

reflection. 

1802.  Chladni's 'Akustik.' 

Count  Rumford's  papers,  which  laid  the  foundation  of  the  mechanical 
explanation  of  heat,  belong  to  the  end  of  the  last  century,  and  in 

1799  H.  Davy  publishes  his  equally  important  'Essay  on  Heat,  Light, 
&c.' 

1800.  Bichat's  '  Recherches  physiologiques.' 

1801.  Bichat's  '  Anatomie  gene"rale.' 

1799-1804.  Alexander  von  Humboldt  travels  in  America,  and  lays  by 
his  observations  the  foundation  of  the  sciences  of  physical 
geography  and  meteorology 

For  the  history  of  the  philosophical  movement  of  thought  the  years 

1793-1806  witnessed  in  Germany  the  great  development,  expansion,  and 
criticism  of  Kant's  ideas  in  the  writings  of 

1793    Schiller,  '  Briefe  iiber  iisthetische  Erziehung.' 

1796.  Schiller,  'tJber  naive  und  sentimentalische  Dichtung.' 

1797.  Fichte,  '  Wissenschaf tslehre.' 
1797.  Schelling,  '  Naturphilosophie.' 

1803.  Schelling,  '  Transcendentaler  Idealismus.' 

1799.  Schleiermacher,  '  Reden  iiber  die  Religion.' 

1800.  Schleiermacher,  'Monologen.' 
1799.  Herder,  '  Metakritik.' 

1799.  Jacobi,  '  Offener  Brief  an  Fichte.' 
1806.  Hegel,  '  Phiinomenologie  des  Geistes.' 
In  France — 

1804.  Destutt  de  Tracy's  'Ideologic'  represents  the  reigning  philo- 

sophy, and 

1803  Maine  de  Biran's  '  Mdmoire  sur  1'Habitude  '  the  beginning  of  the 

later  reaction  against  it. 
In  England— 
1792-1827.   Dugald  Stewart's  '  Elements  of  the  Human  Mind '  and  his 


84  INTRODUCTION. 

To  it  are  due  the  great  changes  in  every  department  of 
science,  of  life,  and  probably  also  of  literature  and  art, 
the  great  inventions  and  the  great  conflicts  of  our  age. 
Science  has  not  only  very  largely  influenced  our  ideas, 
it  has  also  by  its  applications  altered  the  external  face 
of  the  world  we  live  in.  It  is  therefore  simply  a  tribute 
to  the  popular  view,  and  a  desire  to  start  from  some 
striking  and  generally  conceded  position,  if  I  select  the 
39.  scientific  movement  of  ideas  as  the  first  with  which 

Scientific 

progress  to    I  have  to  deal.     How  has  it  spread  in  the  course  of 

be  consid- 
ered first.      the  century  ?     From  what  beginnings  and  through  what 

influences  ?  What  are  its  principles  and  methods  ?  How 
have  they  themselves  changed  and  developed  ?  What 
has  it  led  to  ?  These  are  some  of  the  questions  which 

1803  '  Life  and  Writings  of  Thomas  Reid  '  represent  the  predominant 

Scottish  philosophy,  and 

1804  Thomas  Brown,  '  Inquiry  into  the  Relation  of  Cause  and  Effect,' 

the  beginnings  of  the  later  associationalist  school.  At  the  same 
period  Jeremy  Bentham's  influence,  which  cannot  be  reduced  to 
special  dates,  had  already  acquired  European  if  not  world-wide 
importance.  His  long  life  (1748-1832)  was  contemporary  with 
Goethe's  (1749-1832),  whose  '  Faust'  was  given  to  the  world  in 
successive  stages  between  the  years  1790  and  1832. 

1794.  Thomas  Paine's  'Age  of  Reason.' 

1798.  Malthus's  'Principles  of  Population.' 

Literary  criticism  started  on  a  new  era  and  extended  its  influence  in 

1802    through  the  'Edinburgh  Review,'  and 

1808    the  '  Quarterly  Review  ' ;  in  Germany  somewhat  earlier  in 

1794    Schiller s  'Horen.' 

1797.  Schiller  and  Goethe's  "Xenien"  in  the  '  Musenalmauach.' 

1798.  SchlegeFs  'Athenaeum.' 

1802.  A.  W.  v.  Schlegel's  Berlin  lectures. 

The  Romantic  school  of  fiction  dates  in  Germany  from  1798,  when 
Frederick  Schlegel  uses  the  term  for  the  first  time  as  characteristic  of 
a  new  departure  in  his  review  of  Goethe's  '  Wilhelm-Meister '  ('  Athenaeum,' 
vol.  i.)  A  literary  movement  with  frequently  similar  aims  and  charac- 
teristics is  represented  in  this  country  by  Walter  Scott  ("  Lay  of  the  Last 
Minstrel,"  1805),  Southey  ("  Thalaba,"  1802),  and  Coleridge  ("  Christabel," 
1806),  and  spreads  later  into  France.  As  the  great  source  of  the  new 
and  original  poetic  inspiration  of  nineteenth-century  poetiy  we  have  the 
"  Lyrical  Ballads,"  1798,  and  besides  '  Faust,'  the  other  principal  works  of 
Goethe  and  Schiller  (died  1805). 


INTRODUCTION.  85 

I  shall  try  to  answer  as  concisely  as  possible.  This 
selection  does  not  commit  me  to  any  theory  on  the 
value  of  the  scientific  view  as  compared  with  other 
aspects.  Such  theories  will  have  to  be  dealt  with  in  a 
later  portion  of  the  work.  They  have  sprung  up  in  the 
course  of  the  last  hundred  years,  partly  as  the  inevitable 
outcome  of  scientific  progress  itself,  partly  in  the  educa- 
tional world,  where  a  reaction  has  set  in  against  the 
undue  importance  which  former  generations  attached  to 
classical  learning  and  training.  I  need  not  at  present 
do  more  than  note  these  opinions,  nor  need  I  define 
my  position  with  regard  to  Comte's  celebrated  positivist 
theory  on  the  advancing  stages  of  the  human  intellect. 
Curiosity  and  the  consensus  of  popular  opinion  suffice 
for  the  moment  to  make  me  take  up  the  scientific  side 
of  the  thought  of  the  age.  As  we  proceed,  other  directions 
and  movements  will  present  themselves,  and  the  inter- 
dependence of  all  human -interests  will  reveal  and  explain  40. 
what  truth  attaches  to  Hegel's  celebrated  doctrine  of  the  trfneofthe 

spontaneous 

inherent  dialectic  of  ideas,  the  spontaneous  development  JJf™^ 
of  thought.  tiiougu. 


A  HISTORY  OF  EUROPEAN  THOUGHT  IN 
THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY 


PART  I. 
SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT 


89 


CHAPTER    I. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   FRANCE. 


IT  will  be  generally  admitted  that  the  scientific  spirit  is        i. 

Our  century 

a  prominent  feature  of  the  thought  of  our  century  as  the  scientific 

century. 

compared  with  other  ages.  Some  may  indeed  be  in- 
clined to  look  upon  science  as  the  main  characteristic 
of  this  age.  The  century  may  thus  be  called  with  some 
propriety  the  scientific  century,  as  the  last  was  called  the 
philosophical  century,  or  as  the  sixteenth  was  termed  the 
century  of  the  Reformation  and  the  fifteenth  the  century 
of  the  Eenaissance.  It  is  therefore  natural  that  we  should 
begin  our  study  of  the  thought  of  the  age  with  an  ex- 
amination of  this  side  of  modern  culture. 

It  is  not  necessary  to  define  what  I  mean  by  science.1 


1  The  use  of  the  word  science 
and  its  adjective  scientific  has 
varied  considerably  in  the  English 
language.  We  must  wait  for  Dr 
Murray's  great  work  to  give  us  a 
history  of  the  word.  I  venture  to 
assert  that  it  acquired  its  present 
definite  meaning  about  the  time  of 
the  formation  of  the  British  Asso- 
ciation for  the  Advancement  of 
Science  (1831).  The  two  other 
great  organisations  which  profes- 


sedly started  for  the  culture  of 
what  we  now  call  science  —  viz., 
the  Royal  Society  for  the  Improve- 
ment of  Natural  Knowledge,  and 
the  Royal  Institution — did  not  use 
the  word  officially  in  their  charter 
or  title,  although  it  is  used  fre- 
quently in  the  documents  and  cor- 
respondence connected  with  the 
foundation  of  the  younger,  and 
occasionally  in  those  referring  to 
the  older  Society.  The  Royal  So- 


90 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


Schools  and  colleges  of  science,  triposes,  examinations, 
and  degrees  in  science,  have  established  a  popular  mean- 
ing which  did  not  exist  a  hundred  years  ago,  but  which 
is  now  well  understood.  For  my  purpose  it  is  of  some 
interest  to  note  that  the  meaning  of  the  word  in  French 
is  somewhat  different,  and  that  the  word  Wissenschaft,1 


ciety,  and  sometimes  the  Royal 
Institution,  use  the  word  "philo- 
sophy" in  formal  and  official  state- 
ments of  their  object.  This  is  in 
accordance  with  older  English 
usage.  What  we  now  universally 
call  science  was  not  infrequently 
termed  in  the  seventeenth  century 
natural  knowledge,  and  Bacon  him- 
self translates  scientice  by  "  know- 
ledge," by  "learning,"  and  some- 
times by  "sciences."  In  France, 
on  the  other  hand,  the  word  "  sci- 
ence" seems  to  have  acquired  its 
present  meaning  as  far  back  as  the 
middle  of  the  seventeenth  century. 
At  the  time  of  the  foundation  of 
the  "  Academic  des  Sciences,"  in 
1666,  the  word  was  used  almost  in 
the  same  sense  —  embracing  the 
same  separate  departments  of  know- 
ledge— as  the  word  "science"  is  now 
used  in  this  country  when  we  speak 
of  a  college  of  science.  In  France, 
so  far  as  I  am  aware,  a  cultivator 
of  science  has  never  been  called  a 
philosopher.  Science  and  philos- 
ophy have  there  never  been  synony- 
mous. But  science  in  France  has 
been  made  to  cover  a  larger  field 
of  knowledge  by  such  adjectives  as 
"moral,"  "social,"  "political,"  and 
has  been  narrowed  by  such  other 
adjectives  as  "exact"  and  "natural," 
in  the  same  way  as  the  word  philo- 
sophy has  been  more  strictly  defined 
in  the  English  language  by  the  ad- 
jectives "  natural,"  "  experimental," 
"moral,"  "mental,"  &c.  At  the 
head  of  the  sciences  in  France  stood 
"mathematics,"  at  the  base  of  the 


new  philosophy  in  England  stood 
"experiment"  and  "observation." 
1  The    word    Wissenschaft  has  a 
much  wider  meaning  than  science 
in    the   modern   sense,   and  is  the 
literal    translation    of    the    Latin 
scientia.     It   means    knowledge   in 
a  systematic  form   and   connected 
by  some  method.  What  the  French 
call  science,  the  Germans  call  exacte 
Wissenschaft.   This  includes  mathe- 
matics and  Naturwisscnschaft,  which 
covers  the  ground  covered  by  the 
word  "sciences"  in  English.     The 
word  Wissenschaft  plays  an  import- 
ant part  in  German  culture,  as  we 
shall    see    later    on.     The    modern 
term  "scientist"  is  about  synony- 
mous with  the  word  Naturforscher 
in   German.     The  word   savant   in 
French  has  no  synonym  in  English, 
but  is  about  equivalent  to  the  term 
Gelchrter    in    German ;    and    this, 
again,    is    partially    translated    by 
"scholar"  in   English.     I   suppose 
"man  of  science"  and  "scholar" 
together  would  be  about  covered  by 
either  savant  or  Gelehrter.     Those 
who  desire  to  study  the  older  and 
modern,   the  English  and  foreign, 
uses  of  the  word  science  and  othci 
kindred  terms,  should  read  Bacon '- 
English  writings  ;  Weld's  '  History 
of  the  Royal  Society '  (1848,  vol.  i.) ; 
Bence  Jones's  '  The  Royal  Institu- 
tion' (1871);  Le"on  Aucoc's  'L'lnsti- 
tut  de  France'  (Paris,  1889) ;  Alfred 
Maury,  '  Les  Academies  d'autrefois ' 
(vol.  i.,  Paris,  1864)  ;  and  the  cor- 
respondence in  connection  with  the 
foundation  of  the  British  Associa- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


91 


by  which  science  is  translated  into  German,  requires  a 
qualification  in  order  to  cover  approximately  the  same 
ground.  These  verbal  differences  point  to  differences  of  2. 

.  Difference  of 

thought.     Only  since  Continental  ideas   and   influences  English  and 

Continental 

have  gained  ground  in  this  country  has  the  word  science  n°tionsof 

<f  science. 

gradually  taken  the  place  of  that  which  used  to  be 
termed  natural  philosophy  or  simply  philosophy.  One 
reason  why  science  forms  such  a  prominent  feature  in 
the  culture  of  this  age  is  the  fact  that  only  within  the 
last  hundred  years  has  scientific  research  approached  the 
more  intricate  phenomena  and  the  more  hidden  forces 
and  conditions  which  make  up  and  govern  our  everyday 
life.  The  great  inventions  of  the  sixteenth,  seventeenth, 
and  eighteenth  centuries  were  made  without  special 
scientific  knowledge,  and  frequently  by  persons  who 
possessed  skill  rather  than  learning.  They  greatly  in- 
fluenced science  and  promoted  knowledge,  but  they  were 
brought  about  more  by  accident  or  by  the  practical  re- 
quirements of  the  age  than  by  the  power  of  an  unusual 
insight  acquired  by  study.1  But  in  the  course  of  the  last 


tion  in  Dr  WhewelFs  '  Writings  and 
Correspondence'  by  Todhunter  (2 
vols.,  London,  1876).  I  believe  the 
word  philosophy  has  lost  the  specific 
meaning  which  it  acquired  in  the 
Baconian  school,  as  much  through 
the  influence  of  French  science  on 
the  one  side  as  through  that  of 
metaphysics  on  the  other.  The 
latter  emanated  from  Scotland,  and 
from  Germany  through  Coleridge. 
It  reinstated  the  word  philosophy 
in  its  original  sense. 

1  Examples  are  plentiful.  Not  to 
speak  of  gunpowder  and  printing, 
which  came  earlier,  we  have  later 
nearly  all  the  great  improvements 


connected  with  the  manufacture  of 
textiles,  the  fly-shuttle,  the  self- 
acting  mule,  the  power-loom,  the 
spinning -roller,  invented  by  men 
of  little  or  no  scientific  education. 
The  same  is  the  case  with  the 
older  metallurgical  processes,  the 
refining  of  copper  and  the  intro- 
duction of  cast  -  iron.  Watt  was 
one  of  the  first  who  brought  a 
trained  intellect  to  his  mechan- 
ical work.  The  Royal  Society  was 
started  with  the  distinct  purpose 
of  cultivating  such  knowledge  as 
has  "  a  tendency  to  use " ;  the 
Royal  Institution  still  more  so.  It 
is,  however,  still  doubtful,  view- 


92  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

hundred  years  the  scientific  investigation  of  chemical  and 
electric  phenomena  has  taught  us  to  disentangle  the 
intricate  web  of  the  elementary  forces  of  nature,  to  lay 
bare  the  many  interwoven  threads,  to  break  up  the  equili- 
brium of  actual  existence,  and  to  bring  within  our  power 
and  under  our  control  forces  of  undreamed-of  magnitude. 
3.  The  great  inventions  of  former  ages  were  made  in  countries 

Relation  of 

science  and    where  practical  life,  industry,  and  commerce  were  most 

practical 

advanced ;  but  the  great  inventions  of  the  last  fifty  years 
in  chemistry  and  electricity  and  the  science  of  heat  have 
been  made  in  the  scientific  laboratory :  the  former  were 
stimulated  by  practical  wants ;  the  latter  themselves  pro- 
duced new  practical  requirements,  and  created  new  spheres 
of  labour,  industry,  and  commerce.  Science  and  know- 
ledge have  in  the  course  of  this  century  overtaken  the 
march  of  practical  life  in  many  directions.1  A  confused 

ing    the    history    of    the    learned  especially   medical    substances — by 

societies  as  well  as  the  rare  cases  in  chemical   synthesis.      The   occupa- 

which   highest   scientific  genius  is  tion  with  this  problem  under  A.  W. 

allied  with    practical   skill   in   the  Hofmann's  instructions  led  Perkiu 

same  person,  whether  the  cultiva-  in  1856  to  the  discovery  of  the  first 

tion  of  research  for  its  own  sake  anilin    colour   (Mauvein,   see   'Ber- 

should  not  preferably  be  kept  dis-  ichte    der    deutschen    chemischen 

tinct   from    its    hasty    application.  Gesellschaft,'    Xo.     17,    p.     3391 ». 

This  is  the  view  held  by  many  great  Leblanc's   discovery  how   to   make 

thinkers  abroad.     In   England  the  carbonate   of    soda  from   salt,   for 

opposite  view   has  frequently  im-  which  a  prize  had  been  offered  by 

peded  the  progress  of  pure  science.  the  Paris  Academy  uuder  Napoleon, 

1  A   few  examples   may   suffice.  led  to  the  enormous  development 

The  discovery  by  Oersted  and  Am-  of   the  sulphuric  acid  industry  in 

pere    of    Electromagnetism    (1819,  England    and    on    the    Continent. 

1820)   led  at  once  to  the  idea  of  Liebig  foretold  in  1840  the  recovery 

electrical  telegraphy  :  the  first  tele-  of  sulphur  from  the  waste  of  chemi- 

graph   over  considerable   distances  cal   works   and   the  effect    on    the 

was     constructed    by    Gauss     and  sulphur  mines  of  Sicily,  fifty  years 

Weber     (see     '  Wilhelm     Weber,'  before  this  process  was  satisfactorily 

Breslau,    1893,    p.    26,    &c.)     The  carried   out   (see   Liebig's   familiar 

artificial  preparation  of  an  organic  '  Letters  on  Chemistry,'  1st  ed.,  1843, 

substance  by  Wohler  in  1828  led  at  pp.  22,  31,  &c.)     But  the  greatest 

once  to  many  attempts  at  prepar-  of    all    industries    created    in    the 

ing  expensive  organic  compounds —  laboratory    was    probably    that    of 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


93 


picture  of  this  latest  stage  of  culture  lived  in  the  pro-        4. 

Foreseen  by 

phetie  but  essentially  unscientific  mind  of  Lord  Bacon.  Lord  Bacon. 
But  he -did  not  sufficiently  allow  for  the  amount  of  patient 
scientific  toil  that  was  needed,  nor  for  the  time  which  the 
preparation  of  the  instruments  of  research  would  require, 
nor  for  the  necessity  of  destroying  existing  superstition 
and  accumulated  errors.  All  that  has  since  been  done  by 
Newton  and  the  great  Continental  mathematicians  in  the 
former,  and  by  Bayle  and  Voltaire  in  the  latter  sense, 
Bacon  had  hoped  to  achieve  at  once  by  the  new  philo- 
sophy of  fruit  and  progress.  Such  expectations  were 
inevitably  doomed  to  disappointment,  though  posterity 
has  made  amends  by  all  but  universally  referring  to  him 
as  the  pioneer  of  modern  thought, — as  the  herald  of  a 
new  era  of  human  civilisation.1 


making  artificially  the  fertilising 
compounds  required  in  common 
agriculture  which  followed  on  the 
publication  of  Liebig's  famous  work 
on  '  Chemistry  in  its  applications 
to  Agriculture  and  Physiology'  in 
1840  (see  Hofmann's  Faraday 
Lecture  of  1875,  'The  Lifework  of 
Liebig,'  p.  15,  &c.)  Liebig  also 
discovered  and  described  in  1832 
the  properties  of  chloroform  and 
chloral,  fifteen  years  before  Simpson 
introduced  the  first  as  an  anaesthetic 
and  twenty  years  before  Oscar 
Liebreich  discovered  the  physiolog- 
ical action  of  chloral  (ibid.,  p.  101, 
&c.)  Sir  Lowthian  Bell  calculated, 
many  years  before  the  invention 
of  the  so-called  basic  process  of 
making  steel,  the  fertilising  value 
of  the  phosphorus  which  was  con- 
tained in  the  ironstone  of  Cleve- 
land, and  which  then  made  it  use- 
less for  the  manufacture  of  high- 
class  iron  and  steel.  The  great 
revolution  in  the  theory  of  the 


steam-engine  embodied  in  the  work 
of  Macquorn  Rankine  is  to  be  traced 
back  to  the  patient  measurements 
by  Joule  of  the  mechanical  equiva- 
lent of  heat. 

1  A  great  controversy  arose  on 
this  subject  through  the  publica- 
tion of  Liebig's  pamphlet  in  1862, 
entitled,  '  Francis  Bacon  von  Veru- 
lam  und  die  Methode  der  Natur- 
forschung.'  It  was  directed  mostly 
against  the  exaggerated  view  taken 
by  Macaulay  in  his  celebrated  essay. 
The  fact  is  that  Bacon,  like  Vol- 
taire after  him,  was  much  more 
of  an  essayist  and  a  man  of  the 
world  than  a  patient  labourer  in 
any  special  field  of  research  ;  he 
was  more  of  a  philosopher  in  a 
worldly  sense  (what  the  Germans 
call  "  ein  Weltweiser")  than  a  pro- 
found thinker.  He  misunderstood 
many  of  the  great  discoveries  of  his 
age,  though  he  prophetically  fore- 
saw tbe  great  change  in  the  spirit 
of  inquiry.  He  did  not  appreciate 


94 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


5. 

Defect  in 
Bacon's 
philosophy. 


Our  age  has  in  many  ways  inherited  the  spirit  of 
Bacon's  philosophy ;  but  it  would  be  a  mistake  to  attri- 
bute its  great  scientific  achievements  to  the  exclusive 
working  of  this  spirit.  Bacon  was  neither  a  retired  and 
patient  nor  an  accurate  thinker — the  desire  to  apply  and 
make  his  learning  useful  led  him  away  from  the  "  sapien- 
tiun  templa  serena  "  into  the  forum  of  life :  in  his  own 
experience,  as  well  as  in  his  writings,  he  anticipated  many 
of  the  dangers  which  beset  modern  culture — the  love  of 
premature  application,  and  the  haste  for  practical  results 
and  achievements.  Science,  which  in  the  hands  of  patient 
and  diligent  observers l  had  just  been  rescued  from  the 
sway  of  empty  metaphysical  and  theological  reasoning, 


the  enormous  part  which  mathe- 
matics would  play  in  the  develop- 
ment of  science.  In  this  respect 
Descartes  was  a  genius  of  much 
greater  originality — his  actual  con- 
tributions to  scientific  progress,  as 
well  as  those  of  Pascal,  being  far 
beyond  those  of  Bacon ;  but  they 
both  retained  the  metaphysical 
habit  of  thought  which  has  char- 
acterised many,  if  not  all,  among 
the  greatest  mathematicians.  In 
modern  culture  the  popularisation 
of  novel  views  and  ideas  has  become 
so  important  a  factor  that  writers 
like  Bacon  and  Voltaire,  who  com- 
bine the  scientific  and  literary  taste, 
are  of  the  greatest  importance  in 
the  diffusion  of  new  ideas,  though 
none  of  their  works  need  be  looked 
upon  as  great  repositories  of  re- 
search and  knowledge.  Before  Lie- 
big  wrote  his  pamphlet,  a  very  im- 
partial and  temperate  estimate  of 
Bacon's  philosophy  and  its  relations 
to  actual  science  was  published  by 
Robert  Leslie  Ellis  in  his  introduc- 
tion to  the  philosophical  works  of 
Lord  Bacon  (London,  1857).  As 


the  literature  of  the  subject  is  so 
large,  I  cannot  but  recommend  this 
essay  as  containing  one  of  the  best 
discussions  of  it. 

1  A  very  good  and  concise  account 
of  the  achievements  of  these  con- 
temporaries and  forerunners  of  Ba- 
con—of Tycho  (1546-1601),  Kepler 
(1571-1630),  Galileo  (1564-1642\ 
Gilbert  (1540-1603,  Harriot  1560- 
1621),  Napier  (1550-1617),  Harvey 
(1578-1656)  —  is  given  by  John 
Xichol  in  the  second  volume  of  his 
1  Francis  Bacon,  his  Life  and  Philo- 
sophy* (Edinb.,  1889),  pp.  86;  254. 
In  the  same  volume  (p.  193  there 
is  also  a  useful  summary  of  Bacon's 
real  claims  to  a  place  among  physi- 
cists, of  his  ignorances  (p.  196),  and 
of  the  reception  which  his  works 
met  with  in  England  and  abroad 
(p.  233  to  end).  Not  quite  so  read- 
able, but  more  complete,  is  the 
little  volume  of  Hans  Heussler, 
'  F.  Bacon  und  seine  geschichtliche 
Stellung'  (Breslau,  1889  ,  with  its 
flood  of  references — which  exhaust 
the  subject.  See  especially  p.  160, 
&c. .  on  Bacon's  anticipations. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN    FRANCE.  95 

was  in  danger  of  falling  a  prey  to  hasty  generalisation 
for  the  purpose  of  practical  ends.  Practical  demands 
threatened  then,  as  they  frequently  still  do,  to  stifle  or 
to  force  into  premature  growth  the  patient  thought  which 
had  just  begun  to  germinate  in  the  new  light  and  freedom 
of  reason.  The  narrow  view  had  indeed  been  widened, 
and  the  breadth  of  the  land  had  been  surveyed,  but  there 
was  little  inclination  to  deepen  the  view,  or  to  do  more 
than  search  on  the  surface.  The  spirit  of  Bacon's  philo- 
sophy required  a  corrective.  For  a  long  time  to  come  the 
hope  of  practical  application  had  to  be  postponed ;  the 
thinker  and  student  had  to  retire  into  solitude,  and  there 
to  lay  the  more  permanent  foundations  of  the  new  re-  e. 

Corrected 

search.     This  was  done  by  Newton  for  all  time.     His  fey  Newton. 
reputation  spread  more  slowly  than  that  of   the   great 
High    Chancellor;   but  it  rests  on   a   surer  foundation, 
which  baffles  every  attempt  to  shake  it,  and  will  outlast 
all  coming  changes  of  thought. 

The  beginnings  of  modern  scientific  thought  are  thus  to 
be  found  in  this  country.  Lord  Bacon  foretold  propheti- 
cally the  great  change  which  the  new  philosophy  was 
destined  to  work.  Newton  more  patiently  drew  up  the 
first  simple  rules  and  gave  the  first  brilliant  application. 
More  than  the  unfinished  and  wearisome  pages  of  Bacon's 
'  Novum  Organum '  does  the  '  Principia '  deserve  to  be 
placed  on  a  line  with  Aristotle  and  Euclid  as  a  model 
work  of  scientific  inquiry. 

For  a  real  recognition  of  the  greatness  of  Newton,  as  well        7. 

Bacon's  and 

as  for  a  partial  realisation  of  Bacon's  plans,  we  are,  however,  j^^ 
mainly  indebted  to  the  French  philosophers  of  the  second  French  p 
half  of  the  eighteenth  century.  Bacon's  plan  of  promoting  Ob0phers- 


96  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

knowledge  and  research  by  the  co-operation  of  many  was 
more  thoroughly  realised  in  the  old  French  Academy 
than  in  the  Eoyal  Society  of  London :  his  desire  to  unite 
all  knowledge  in  a  collective  work  underlies  the  great 
productions  of  Bayle,  and  still  more  those  of  the  Ency- 
clopaedists. The  many  problems  contained  in  Newton's 
'  Principia '  were  first  treated  singly  by  Clairault  and 
Maupertuis;  a  general  knowledge  of  his  view  of  the 
universe  was  introduced  into  popular  literature  by  Vol- 
taire,1 who  made  use  of  it  as  a  powerful  weapon  wherewith 
to  combat  error  and  superstition,  or,  as  he  termed  it,  "  pour 
^eraser  1'infame " ;  but  for  a  full  announcement  of  its 
scientific  value  and  its  hidden  resources  we  are  indebted 
to  Laplace,  whose  '  Mecanique  celeste '  was  the  first 
comprehensive  elaboration  of  Newton's  ideas,  and  whose 
'  Systeme  du  Monde '  became  the  scientific  gospel  of  a 
whole  generation  of  Continental  thinkers, 
s.  We  may  look  upon  Lord  Bacon  as  one  who  inspects  a 

Bacon  and 

Newton       large  and  newly  discovered  land,"  laying  plans  for  the 

1  I  believe  Voltaire  was  the  author  •    On  this  Mr  Ellis  remarks  (Bacon's 
of  the  term  Newtonianisme.     The  Works,  vol.  i.  p.  63) :   "  Bacon  has 
modesty  and  truly  scientific  spirit  teen  likened  to  the  prophet  who, 
of  Newton  would  not  have  allowed  from  Mount  Pisgah,  surveyed  the 
him  to  apply  such  a   term  to  his  j    Promised  Land,  but  left  it  for  others 
work,  and  it  is  doubtful  whether  ,   to  take  possession  of.     Of  this  happy 
Voltaire     did     not    extract    from  i   image,  perhaps  part  of  the  felicity 
Newton's  '  Philosophia  Naturalis '  a  I   was  not   perceived   by  its   author, 
general  philosophy  which  was  not  For  though  Pisgah  was  a  place  of 
conceived  in  his  spirit.  I   large  prospect,  yet  still  the  Prom- 

2  Cowley  in  his  Ode  to  the  Royal  j   ised  Land   was  a  land   of  definite 
Society  : —  \   extent  and  known  boundaries,  and, 


"  Bacon  at  last,  a  mighty  man,  arose,  .  .  . 
And  boldly  undertook  the  injur'cl  pupil's 


cause. 


led  us  forth  at  last, 
The  barren  wilderness  he  past ; 
Did  on  the  very  border  stand 
Of  the  blest  promis'd  land  ; 


moreover,  it  was  certain  that  after 
no  long  time  the  chosen  people 
would  be  in  possession  of  it  all. 
And  this  agrees  with  what  Bacon 
promised  to  himself  and  to  man- 
kind from  the  iustauration  of  the 


And,  from  the  mountain's  top  of  his  ex- 
alted wit,  >    sciences.  ...  In  this  respect,  as  in 
Saw  it  himself,  and  shew'd  us  it."  others,  the  hopes  of  Francis  Bacon 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


97 


development  of  its  resources  and  the  gathering  of  its 
riches.  But  the  wealth  lies  deep  down,  and  is  only  indi- 
cated by  the  first  labours  of  the  early  pioneers.  Newton, 
following  these,  unites  their  beginnings  into  a  systematic 
exploration,  and  sinks  the  main  shaft  which  reaches  the 
lode  of  rich  ore.  He  opens  out  the  wealth  of  the  mine 
and  marks  out  the  work  for  his  followers.  But  many 
difficulties  had  to  be  overcome,  much  united  effort  and 
a  vast  organisation  of  labour  were  required,  in  order  to 
develop  to  the  full  Newton's  scheme,  and  to  raise  the 
great  treasure  which  he  had  reached.  This  was  not  done 
until  the  end  of  the  last  century,  when  Laplace  collected, 
arranged,  and  condensed  the  work  of  French  and  English 
mathematicians  and  observers  into  a  picture  of  the  uni- 
verse. A  variety  of  circumstances  had  combined  to  make 
the  French  capital  the  place  above  all  others  where  the 
means  and  materials  for  the  development  of  the  great 
work  could  be  most  easily  procured.  Let  us  glance  for 
a  moment  at  the  different  factors  in  operation  during 
the  eighteenth  century  which  contributed  to  the  great 
.achievement. 

Whilst  Newton  was  labouring  privately  and  almost 
unassisted1  at  the  greatest  scientific  work  produced  in 


were  not  destined  to  be  fulfilled. 
It  is  neither  to  the  technical  part 
of  his  method,  nor  to  the  details  of 
his  view  of  the  nature  and  progress 
of  science,  that  his  great  fame  is 
justly  owing.  His  merits  are  of 
another  kind.  They  belong  to  the 
spirit  rather  than  to  the  positive 
precepts  of  his  philosophy." 

1  It  has  been  stated  that  New- 
ton, not  knowing  of  Norwood's  ap- 
proximately correct  determination 

VOL.  I. 


of  the  length  of  a  degree  in  1635 
(published  in  his  'Seaman's  Prac- 
tice' in  1637),  but  relying  on  the 
old  figure  of  sixty  miles  for  a  de- 
gree of  latitude  (confirmed  by  Ed. 
Wright,  Cambridge,  1610),  was  led 
away  from  the  right  supposition, 
which  he  entertained  as  far  back  as 
1665,  regarding  the  moon's  orbit, 
and  had  to  wait  for  Picard's  figures 
(ascertained  about  1669,  published 
in  France  about  1672,  and  in  the 

G 


Laplace's 


98 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


modern  times  by  any  single  mind,1  the  penetrating  and 
far-seeing  genius  of  Colbert  had  already  recognised  the 
important  part  which  science  would  one  day  play  in 
the  government  of  the  world,  and  had  secured  the  ap- 
proval of  his  royal  master  to  the  constitution  of  an  Aca- 


Philos.  Transactions  in  1675),  by 
applying  which  he  determined  that 
"  the  moon  appeared  to  be  kept  in 
her  orbit  purely  by  the  power  of 
gravity."  See  Brewster's  'Life  of 
Newton,'  vol.  L  p.  290,  &c.;  Tod- 
hunter's  '  History  of  the  Theories  of 
Attraction,"  vol.  i.  p.  38,  Ac.  This 
account  is,  however,  now  discredited 
(see  infra,  chap,  iv.)  For  the  part 
which  Dr  Hooke  and  Halley  took  in 
the  discovery  of  the  "reciprocal 
duplicate  "  ratio,  see  also  Brewster, 
loc.  cit.,  vol.  i.  p.  291,  &c.  During 
the  writing  of  the 'Principia3  New- 
ton carried  on  a  useful  correspond- 
ence with  Flamsteed,  who  was  then 
Astronomer-Koyal.  How  this  happy 
co-operation  ceased  ten  years  later 
can  be  read  at  length  in  Brewster 
(loc.  cit.,vo\.  i.  p.  312;  vol.  ii.  p.  164, 
&c.)  The  greatest  material  assist- 
ance which  Newton  received  was 
from  Halley,  who  defrayed  the  ex- 
penses of  publishing  the  '  Principia,' 
after  the  Royal  Society,  to  which  it 
was  dedicated,  had  reversed  its  resol- 
ution to  defray  them  (Brewster,  vol. 
i.  p.  305,  &c.)  Nevertheless  Weld,  in 
his  'History  of  the  Royal  Society,' 
says  :  "  Fortunate  indeed  was  it  for 
science  that  such  a  body  as  the  Royal  I 
Society  existed,  to  whom  Newton  ' 
could  make  his  scientific  communi- 
cations ;  otherwise  it  is  very  possible 
that  the  '  Principia  '  would  never 
have  seen  the  light."  Though  one 
must  lament  the  differences  be- 
tween Flamsteed  and  Newton,  which 
prevented  the  latter  from  bring- 
ing his  investigations  of  the  lunar 
and  planetary  theories  to  a  close 
(Brewster,  vol.  i.  p.  312),  a  word  of 


deep  gratitude  is  due  to  Flamsteed's 
own  exertions  in  the  cause  of  astro- 
nomy. After  Charles  II.  had  built 
the  Observatory  in  order  to  have 
the  places  of  the  fixed  stars  ' '  anew 
observed,  examined,  and  corrected 
for  the  use  of  his  seamen :!  (Flam- 
steed,  History  of  his  own  Life),  and 
after  he  had  appointed  Flamsteed 
Astronomer -Royal  at  a  salary  of 
£100  per  annum,  the  Observatory, 
"  hurriedly  established,  was  left  for 
a  period  of  nearly  fifteen  years 
without  a  single  instrument  being 
furnished  by  the  Government " 
(Weld,  vol.  i.  p.  255).  The  instru- 
ments were  mostly  supplied  by 
Flamsteed  himself  or  lent  by  others, 
and  besides,  "  the  king  had  ordered 
that  Flamsteed  should  instruct 
monthly  two  boys  from  Christ 
Church  Hospital,  which  was  a  great 
annoyance  to  him,  and  interfered 
with  his  proper  avocations  ''  (Baily, 
'  Account  of  the  Rev.  J.  Flamsteed'). 
"Any  other  man  would  probably 
have  succumbed  under  the  amount 
of  drudgery  appertaining  to  the 
office  (earning  his  salary  by  labour 
harder  than  thrashing),  if  indeed, 
in  the  absence  of  encouragement, 
he  would  have  continued  in  it  at 
all,  and  particularly  when  the  re- 
ward was  so  insignificant"  (Weld, 
vol.  i.  p.  256). 

1  "And  it  may  be  justly  said, 
that  so  many  and  so  valuable  Philo- 
sophical Truths,  as  are  herein  dis- 
covered and  put  past  dispute,  were 
never  yet  owing  to  the  Capacity 
and  Industry  of  any  one  Man '' 
(Words  of  Halley,  Philos.  Transac- 
tions, vol.  xvi.,  1687). 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


99 


demy,  which  was  based  upon  the  endowment  of  research, 
and  which  prompted  the  co-operation  of  its  members  in 
organised l  scientific  work.  Whilst  the  Koyal  Society  of 
London  only  received  a  charter,  and  existed  by  the  en- 
trance payments  and  contributions  of  its  own  members, 
augmented  by  private  donations,  the  Paris  Academy  had,  10. 
as  far  back  as  1671,  received  the  funds  with  which  to  Academy 

of  Sciences. 

commence  its  labours  in  connection  with  the  survey  of 
the  kingdom  and  its  extensive  dependencies.  It  was  these 
labours  which  led  to  the  measurements  of  the  length  of 
the  seconds  pendulum,  and  of  the  variation  of  gravity  in 
different  latitudes ;  to  the  explanation  of  this  variation 
by  Huygens ;  to  the  controversy  regarding  the  figure  of 
the  earth ;  to  the  direct  measurements  of  the  arcs  of  the 
meridian  in  Peru  and  Lapland  ;  and,  finally,  to  Clairault's 
celebrated  work  on  this  subject.2  It  was  almost  exclu- 
sively by  these  observations  that  the  data  were  found 
with  which  to  substantiate  Newton's  mathematical  reason- 
ings :  in  his  own  country  that  fruitful  co-operation  which 


1  "  Le  roi  assurait  1'existence  des 
Academiciens  par  des  pensions  et 
mettait  liberalement  a  leur  disposi- 
tion un  fonds  destine  a  pourvoir  aux 
frais  de  leurs  experiences  et  de  leurs 
instruments  "  (Maury,  '  Les  Acade- 
mies d'autrefois,'  vol.  i.  p.  13).  Or- 
ganisation and  co-operation  are  diffi- 
cult to  obtain  in  societies  founded 
on  private  and  voluntary  contribu- 
tions. In  England  they  scarcely  ex- 
isted before  the  foundation  of  the 
British  Association,  with  perhaps 
one  illustrious  exception  pointed 
out  by  Struve  ('Description  de  1'Ob- 
servatoire  de  Pulkowa,'  4to,  Pdters- 
bourg,  p.  5) :  "  II  y  a,  dans  1'histoire 
de  1'observatoire  de  Greenwich,  un 
point  tres  remarquable,  savoir  que 


les  astronomes  ont  travaille  sur 
un  meme  plan,  depuis  1'origine  de 
1'etablissement  jusqu'a  1'epoque 
actuelle."  Organisation  and  co- 
operation were  the  order  in  the 
Paris  Academy  from  the  beginning. 
"  On  y  travaillait  de  concert "  ;  and, 
"Des  les  premiers  mois  de  1667, 
Perrault  proposa  un  plan  de  travail 
pour  la  physique,  c'est  a  dire  pour 
1'ensemble  de  1'histoire  naturelle  " 
(Maury,  loc.  cit.,  p.  15). 

2  A  full  account  of  these  is  given 
in  Todhunter  ( '  Hist,  of  Theories  of 
Attraction,  &c.,'  vol.  i.)  Clairault's 
book  was  published  in  1743,  and  had 
the  title,  '  Theorie  de  la  Figure  de 
la  Terre,  tire"e  des  Principes  de 
1' Hydros tatique,  par  Clairault.' 


100 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


11. 

Continental 
methods  in 
mathe- 
matics. 


can  only  be  secured  by  an  academic  organisation  and  by 
endowment  of  research  was  wanting.  No  one  since  the 
time  of  Bacon  had  been  more  impressed  with  this  neces- 
sary condition  of  modern  progress  than  Newton's  great 
rival,  Leibniz,1  much  of  whose  time  was  spent  in  pro- 
moting academies  all  over  Europe — in  Berlin,  St  Peters- 
burg, Dresden,  and  Vienna — and  who  had  himself  been 
early  attracted  to  Paris  and  London  by  the  scientific 
fame  of  their  learned  societies,  though  he  significantly 
pointed  out  the  want  of  activity  and  efficiency  in  the 
early  history  of  the  Eoyal  Society. 

There  was,  moreover,  another  and  independent  line 
of  scientific  thought  which  had  centred  in  France, 
the  development  of  which  came  greatly  to  the  aid  of 
the  students  of  Newton's  work.  This  was  the  purely 
mathematical  elaboration  of  the  various  infinitesimal 
methods  of  the  French  and  English  mathematicians,  by 
which  they  were  all  brought  together,  simplified,  and 
united  into  a  calculus  with  strict  rules,  a  practical  nota- 
tion, and  an  easy  algorithm.  Newton  himself  had  for  the 
purposes  of  his  great  work  invented  a  new  and  powerful 


1  A  collection  of  Leibniz's  writ- 
ings on  this  subject  will  be  found 
in  the  7th  volume  of  M.  Foucher  de 
Careil's  edition  of  Leibniz's  Works. 
Paris,  1875.  Of  the  projects  of 
Leibniz,  only  the  Academy  of  Berlin 
came  into  existence  during  his  life- 
time (1700  and  1701)  ;  the  others 
were  discussed  at  great  length  with 
the  Elector  of  Saxony,  with  the  Em- 
peror, and  with  Peter  the  Great. 
The  Academy  of  St  Petersburg  was 
founded  in  1724,  eight  years  after 
the  death  of  Leibniz.  The  Academy 
of  Vienna  did  not  come  into  life  till 


1846,  and  in  the  same  year  that  of 
Saxony  was  founded,  which  has  its 
seat  at  Leipsic.  Leibniz  had  the 
largest  views  on  academic  life  and 
work  :  they  were  to  embrace  the 
historical  and  philosophical  studies 
as  well  as  the  purely  scientific,  and 
were  to  stand  in  relation  with  the 
higher  and  lower  educational  in- 
stitutions. His  ideas  are  best 
realised  at  Berlin.  See  Jacob 
Grimm's  interesting  discourse,  en- 
titled '  Ueber  Schule  Universitat 
Akademie'  (Kleine  Schriften,  vol. 
i.  p.  211,  &c.) 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


101 


instrument,  afterwards  called  "  the  method  of  fluxions  "  ; 
but  he  had  not  made  it  generally  known  before  the 
invention  of  Leibniz  was  published.1  This,  though  much 
later  in  time,  had  been  perfected  and  applied  by  his 
friends  and  followers  in  a  most  extensive  manner,  and 
had,  in  fact,  become  the  recognised  mathematical  lan- 
guage of  the  Continent.  No  learned  body  did  more  than 
the  Paris  Academicians  to  perfect  (with  purely  scientific 


1  Leibniz  seems  to  have  been  in 
possession  of  his  method  as  early 
as  1675,  and  communicated  it  to 
Collins  in  1677.  It  was,  however, 
not  published  before  1684  in  the 
'  Acta  Eruditorum,'  and  then  prob- 
ably only  on  account  of  some  writ- 
ings of  Tschirnhausen  trenching  on 
the  same  subject.  Newton  seems 
to  have  been  in  possession  of  his 
methods  as  early  as  1665,  fully  ten 
years  before  Leibniz  made  use  of 
his.  Immediately  after  the  publi- 
cation of  Leibniz's  paper  in  1684, 
the  differential  calculus  was  taken 
up  by  the  Continental  mathema- 
ticians, especially  by  James  Ber- 
noulli (1654-1705)  and  John  Ber- 
noulli (1667-1748),  and  the  Mar- 
quis de  1'Hopital,  who  published 
the  first  treatise  on  the  new  calculus 
in  1696.  Newton  did  not  publish 
any  account  of  his  method,  though 
he  must  have  used  it  extensively  in 
arriving  at  the  results  contained 
in  the  'Principia.'  Different  views 
have  been  expressed  on  the  reasons 
which  induced  Newton  to  withhold 
from  publication  his  new  methods, 
and  the  question  to  what  extent 
Leibniz  owed  the  first  suggestions 
of  his  method  to  Newton  remains 
also  undecided.  Those  who  take 
an  interest  in  the  personal  question 
should  refer  to  the  original  docu- 
ments, the  '  Commercium  Epistoli- 
cum,' published  by  the  Royal  Society 
in  1715  ;  the  pamphlet  of  Gerhard t, 


'  Die    Erfindung    der    Differential- 
rechnung'  (Halle,  1848).      An  ex- 
treme view,  unfavourable  to  Leib- 
niz's originality,  is  taken  by  Sloman, 
'  Leibnitzens     Anspruch     auf     die 
Erfindung      der      Differentialrech- 
nung'  (Leipzig,  1857);  but  it  has 
not  been  generally  adopted  by  those 
who  have  examined  into  the  subject. 
As  to  the  superiority  of  the  Conti- 
nental notation  for  practical  pur- 
poses,   this    seems    to    have    been 
generally  admitted  at  the  beginning 
of  this  century,  when  it  was  intro- 
duced  into   English   mathematical 
works.      In  the  school   of   W.   R. 
Hamilton  of  Dublin  the   notation 
used  by  Newton  acquired  a  peculiar 
importance,  and  it  is  still  occasion- 
ally used  in  some  important  works 
like  Tait  and   Steele's   '  Dynamics 
of  a   Particle,'  and  Thomson  and 
Tait's  'Natural  Philosophy.'      See 
on  this  Tait's  article  on  Hamilton  in 
the  '  North  British  Review '  (Sept. 
1866).       The    importance    of    the 
labours  of  the  Continental  school, 
headed  by  Leibniz,  for  the  diffusion 
of  the   new   methods,   is  well  de- 
scribed by  Remont  de  Montmort  in 
a  letter  to  Brook  Taylor,  dated  18th 
December  1718,  and  given   in  the 
appendix    to    Brewster's    '  Life    of 
Newton '  (vol.  Si.  p.  511,  &c.)    Those 
who  take  more  interest  in  the  fate 
of  ideas  and  the  progress  of  thought 
than  in  personal   matters   will  do 
well  to  read  this  letter. 


102  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

interest)  this  new  calculus,  which  in  the  course  of  the 
eighteenth  century  had  in  the  hands  of  Lagrange  been 
adapted  to  all  the  purposes  and  problems  contained  or 
suggested  in  Newton's  '  Principia.' 
12.  This  leads  me  to  a  third  and  yet  more  important  element 

Modem 

analytical     Of  scientific  thought,  which  was  peculiar  to  the  Continental, 

methods. 

and  especially  to  the  French  mathematicians,  counting 
among  them  Leibniz,  who,  though  a  German,  was  wholly 
trained  in  the  French  school.  This  factor  is  the  estab- 
lishment of  pure  mathematics  on  an  independent  founda- 
tion, and  the  cultivation  of  research  into  the  abstract 
relations  of  quantity,  without  reference  either  to  geomet- 
rical or  mechanical  problems  and  applications.  It  is 
the  modern  analytical  spirit  introduced  by  the  great 
French  algebraists  of  the  seventeenth  century,  which 
looks  upon  geometry,  mechanics,  and  astronomy  merely 
as  "  questions  d'analyse,"  and  makes  their  solutions  de- 
pend upon  the  perfecting  of  an  abstract  calculus  rather 
than  on  the  study  of  these  individual  problems  them- 
selves. Opposed  to  this  spirit  of  analysis,  which  in 
general  seeks  the  solution  of  any  given  question  by 
looking  upon  it  as  a  special  case  of  a  wider  and  more 
abstract  problem,  is  the  method  known  to  the  ancients, 
which  never  loses  sight  of  the  actual  application,  be  it  a 
figure  in  geometry  or  a  special  arrangement  of  physical 
forces,  and  is  more  interested  in  the  peculiarities  of  the 
individual  case  than  in  the  abstract  formula  of  which  it 
may  be  considered  an  application.  This  opposite  view 
regards  the  calculus  and  mathematics  in  general  merely 
as  an  instrument,  the  value  of  which  lies  solely  in  its 
application  to  real  physical  problems.  It  is  usually 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


103 


termed  the  synthetical  method,  and  has  in  modern  times        13. 

Older  syn- 

survived  principally  in  England,  where  inductive  reason-  theticai 

r       J  method. 

ing,  based  upon  observation  of  detail,  has  since  the  age 
of  Lord  Bacon  been  most  successfully  cultivated.1  These 
different  ways  of  approaching  the  same  subject  will  fre- 
quently engage  my  attention  in  the  course  of  this  survey  : 
the  greatest  mathematicians  of  modern  times  have  recog- 
nised the  importance  of  both  aspects,  and  the  enormous 
progress  of  the  science  itself  has  depended,  no  doubt,  on  an 
alternating  employment  of  them.  Leibniz  clearly  foresaw 
this  when,  in  his  correspondence  with  Huygens  and  others, 
he  urged  the  necessity  of  not  abandoning  the  purely  geo- 
metrical view,  or  entirely  sacrificing  the  older  for  the 
modern  methods.2  There  can,  however,  be  no  doubt  that 


1  See  on  this  point  the  opinion  of 
an  authority,  Hermann  Hankel,  in 
his  highly  interesting  and  sugges- 
tive lecture, '  Die  Entwickelung  der 
Mathematik  in  den  letzten  Jahr- 
hunderten '  (Tubingen,  1869,  re- 
published  by  P.  du  Bois-Reymond, 
1884).  Speaking  of  the  age  of 
Leibniz  he  says  :  ' '  Though  on  the 
Continent  mathematicians  were  not 
so  conservative  as  in  England,  where 
a  purely  geometrical  exposition  was 
considered  to  be  the  only  one  worthy 
of  mathematics,  yet  the  whole  spirit 
of  that  age  was  directed  to  the  sol- 
ution of  problems  in  geometrical 
clothing,  and  the  result  of  the  cal- 
culus had  mostly  to  be  retranslated 
into  geometrical  forms.  It  is  the  in- 
estimable merit  of  the  great  mathe- 
matician of  Basel,  Leonhard  Euler, 
to  have  freed  the  analytical  calculus 
from  all  geometrical  fetters,  and 
thus  to  have  established  analysis 
as  an  independent  science.  Analy- 
sis places  at  its  entrance  the  con- 
ception of  a  function,  in  order  to 
express  the  mutual  dependence  of 


two  variable  quantities.  .  .  .  The 
abstract  theory  of  functions  is  the 
higher  analysis.  .  .  .  The  concep- 
tion of  a  function  has  been  slowly 
and  hesitatingly  evolved  out  of  spe- 
cial and  subordinate  conceptions. 
It  was  Euler  who  first  established 
it,  making  it  the  foundation  of  the 
entire  analysis,  and  hereby  he  in- 
augurated a  new  period  in  mathe- 
matics "(p.  12,  &c. ) 

2  To  Huygens,  16th  September 
1679  :  "  Je  ue  suis  pas  encor  con- 
tent de  1'Algebre,  en  ce  qu'elle  ne 
donue  ny  les  plus  courtes  voyes,  ny 
les  plus  belles  constructions  de  Ge"o- 
metrie.  .  .  .  Je  croy  qu'il  nous  faut 
encor  une  autre  analyse  proprement 
ge"ometrique  ou  lineaire,  qui  nous 
exprime  directement  situm,  comme 
1'Algebre  exprime  magnitudinem. 
Et  je  croy  d'en  avoir  le  moyen, 
et  qu'on  pourroit  repre'senter  des 
figures  et  mesures  des  machines  et 
mouvements  en  caracteres,  comme 
1'Algebre  represente  les  nombres 
ou  grandeurs"  (Leibniz,  Mathem. 
Werke,  ed.  Gerhardt,  vol.  ii.  p.  19). 


104  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

the  great  success  which  attended  Laplace's  work,  the 
elaboration  of  a  system  of  the  universe  out  of  the  prin- 
ciples of  Newton,  was  largely  due  to  the  perfection  which 
the  analytical  methods  had  gained  in  the  hands  of  his 
predecessors,  and  to  the  skill  with  which  he  himself  re- 
duced the  several  problems  to  purely  analytical  questions. 
But  however  much  exact  methods,  learned  societies, 
and  regal  endowments  may  do  to  promote  the  growth  of 
the  scientific  spirit,  experience  has  shown  that  popular 
favour  and  interest  furnish  a  still  more  effective  stimulus. 
Even  the  most  abstract  reasonings  of  the  mathematician 
require  to  be  brought  into  some  connection  with  the  gen- 
eral concerns  of  mankind,  before  they  can  attract  talent 
from  outside,  or  enter  into  that  healthy  action  and  reaction 
which  are  the  soul  of  all  mental  progress.  In  this  respect, 
also,  France  during  the  second  half  of  the  eighteenth  cen- 
14.  tury  was  far  in  advance  of  other  countries.  No  other  liter- 
of  science  ature  of  that  age  can  be  compared  with  that  of  France,  when 

on  French 

Uteratare-  we  look  at  the  influence  or  the  expression  which  modern 
scientific  views  and  interests  had  already  attained  in  it ; 
and  no  other  country  could  at  the  end  of  the  eighteenth 
century  boast  of  such  splendid  means  of  scientific  instruc- 
tion as  then  existed  in  Paris.  In  two  important  depart- 
ments— the  popularisation  and  the  teaching  of  science — 
France  for  a  long  period  led  the  way.1  A  general  inter- 


To  Bodenhausen  (about  1690)  :  "  I 
am  of  opiniou  that  in  the  problems 
of  ordinary  Geometry  the  methodus 
Yeterum  has  certain  advantages 


nor  utiliorqw"  (ibid.,  voL  vii.  p. 
359).  "  It  is  certain  that  algebra, 
by  reducing  everything  a  situ  ad 
tolam  maffnitudinem,  hereby  very 


over  Analytin  Algebraitam,  and  I      frequently  complicates  things  very 
think  I  have  remarked  to  you  that       much"  (p.  362  . 


there  remains  an  Analytic  geometries 
propria,  toto  c&lo  ab  Algebra  direrta 
et  in  multii  longc  A  Igtbra  compendia- 


1  Perhaps  it  would  be  more  cor- 
rect to  say  that  science  was  fashion- 
able than  that  it  was  popular  in  the 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIKIT   IN    FRANCE. 


105 


est  was  thus  created  in  the  proceedings  and  debates  of  the 
Academy,  and  the  discoveries  of  its  illustrious  members 
found  their  way  into  the  lectures  and  text-books  of  the 
professors.  Whatever  eminence  German  science  may  have 
gained  in  this  century,  from  a  purely  literary  point  of 
view,  through  the  works  of  A.  von  Humboldt,  or  English 
science  through  those  of  Darwin,  the  history  of  both 
literatures  during  the  eighteenth  century  can  be  written 
almost  without  any  reference  to  science  at  all — so  small 
was  the  direct  influence  of  such  giants  as  Newton  and 
Leibniz  on  the  popular  mind.  But  who  could  exclude 
from  a  history  of  the  elegant  literature  of  France  the 
names  of  Voltaire,  of  Buffon,  of  D'Alembert,  or  of  Con- 
dorcet  ?  These  form  a  connecting  link  between  science 
and  general  literature.1  A  study  either  of  English  or 


eighteenth  century  in  France.  But 
it  became  popular  through  the  in- 
fluence of  the  great  schools  of  Paris. 
Before  becoming  popular  with  the 
masses  it  became  so  in  cultivated 
and  literary  circles.  The  result 
has  been  that  science  in  France 
alone  has  attained  to  a  perfect  form 
of  expression.  Whereas  in  other 
countries  the  great  models  of  origi- 
nal research  and  thought  were  writ- 
ten in  the  severe  style  handed  down 
by  the  ancients  (Newton's  'Prin- 
cipia  '  and  Gauss's  '  Disquisitiones 
Arithmetical '),  the  great  work  of 
Lagrange  (the  '  M&anique  analy- 
tique')  is  a  model  of  literary  style 
in  the  modern  sense.  Science  in  our 
age  has  become  popular  through 
its  applications.  It  is  the  utili- 
tarian spirit  that  has  popularised 
science  in  Germany  and  England. 
In  France  alone  science,  before  com- 
ing under  the  influence  of  the  utili- 
tarian, came  under  that  of  the  lit- 
erary spirit.  It  was  the  influence  of 


the  academies  that  brought  this 
about.  See  Maury,  'Les  Acade"- 
mies  d'autrefois,'  vol.  i.  p.  178,  &c. 
More  than  with  Richelieu,  the  in- 
terest in  science  nowadays  is  un- 
fortunately only  too  often  purely 
"  metallic "  (quoted  from  Lord 
Chesterfield's  Letters).  See  also 
on  the  literary  as  compared  with 
the  modern  practical  character  of 
science,  Maury,  ibid.,  p.  161. 

1  "On  erfgeait  meme  en  prin- 
cipe  la  ne'cessite  pour  un  philosophe 
de  ne  rester  etranger  a  aucune 
science.  '  L'esprit  philosophique 
fait  tant  de  progres  en  France  de- 
puis  quarante  ans,'  ecrivait  Voltaire 
a  madame  Du  Chatelet,  en  lui  de"- 
diant  sa  tragedie  d'Alzire,  '  que  si 
Boileau  vivait  encore,  lui  qui  osait 
se  moquer  d'une  femme  de  condi- 
tion, parce  qu'elle  voyait  en  secret 
Roberval  et  Sauveur,  il  serait  oblige* 
de  respecter  et  d'imiter  celles  qui 
profitent  publiquement  cles  lumieres 
des  Maupertuis,  des  Reaumur,  des 


106 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


15. 

Absence  of 
this  influ- 
ence in  Eng- 
land and 
Germany. 


1C. 

Schools  of 
science  in 
Paris. 


of  German  eighteenth-century  literature  does  not  intro- 
duce one  to  the  great  controversies  of  science,  but  a 
study  of  Voltaire  leads  one  into  the  midst  of  the  pro- 
found problems  of  the  Newtonian  and  Cartesian  philo- 
sophy, the  disputes  on  the  correct  measure  of  force.1 
Buffon's  influence,  also,  by  spreading  a  taste  for  the  study 
of  nature  and  by  making  objects  of  natural  history  attrac- 
tive, was  probably  much  more  important  than  his  actual 
contributions  to  the  natural  sciences  themselves.2 

For  the  growth  and  diffusion  of  the  scientific  spirit 
itself,  the  great  schools  in  Paris  were  even  of  greater 
value  than  the  popular  writings  of  Voltaire  and  Buffon. 
Most  of  the  Academicians  were  trained  in  these  schools, 


Mairan,  des  Du  Fay  et  des  Clairault ; 
de  tous  ces  veritables  savants  qui 
n'ont  pour  objet  qu'une  science 
utile,  et  qui,  en  la  reudant  agreable, 
la  rendent  insensiblement  neces- 
saire  a  notre  nation.  Nous  sommes 
au  temps,  j'ose  le  dire,  oil  il  faut 
qu'un  poete  soit  philosophe  et  ou 
une  feinme  peut  Fetre  hardiment.' 
En  parlant  ainsi,  Voltaire  ne  faisait 
qu'exprimer  1'opinion  de  son  siecle, 
et  ambitieux  lui-meme  de  reuuir  le 
titre  de  geometre  h  celui  de  poete  et 
d'historien,  il  s'etait  fait  expliquer 
parmadame  Du  Chateletla  physique 
de  Newton "  (Maury,  '  Les  Acad. 
d'autrefois,'  vol.  i.  p.  156). 

1  See  Maury,  vol.  i.  p.  157,  &c. ; 
and  Du  Bois-Reymond,   "  Voltaire 
als  Naturforscher  "  in  '  Gesammelte 
Reden,'  vol.  i.  p.  1. 

2  "Sans    1' eloquence   de  Buffon, 
la  zoologie  serait  demeuree  encore 
longtemps   le   privilege  d'un   petit 
nombre  ;  elle  cut  laisse"  indifferents 
ceux  que  la  nature  e"meut  moins  que 
le  charme  de  la  parole.     La  vieille 
education    classique   avait    le    tort 
de   nous  laisser  tres-ignorants  des 
choses  du  uionde  cree.     Buffon  com- 


niuniqua  aux  sciences  le  charme  des 
lettres.  La  curiosite  s'eveilla.  et  en 
1760,  Valmont  de  Bomare  put  ouv- 
rir  a  Paris  le  premier  cours  d'his- 
toire  naturelle  ;  il  fut  assidiiment 
suivi :'  (Maury,  vol.  i.  p.  283).  A. 
von  Humboldt  had  a  similar  influ- 
ence in  Berlin  seventy  years  later. 
See  Du  Bois  -  Reymond,  foe.  cit., 
vol.  L  p.  510.  Guardia,  '  Histoire 
de  la  Medecine'  (Paris,  1884),  says 
of  Buffon,  "  Fontenelle  avait  rendu 
la  science  aimable  et  accessible. 
Buffon  1'associa  a  la  philosophic  et 
aux  lettres  et  1'introduisit  defini- 
tivement  dans  la  societe  "  (p.  384). 
What  a  contrast,  when  we  read  in 
the  '  Life  of  Sir  W.  R.  Hamilton ' 
(by  R.  P.  Graves,  vol.  ii.  p.  196) 
that  Dr  Buckland's  communica- 
tion at  the  Bristol  meeting  of  the 
British  Association  (1836)  "  was 
apparently  the  first  occasion  of 
bringing  before  the  public  mind  in 
England  the  geological  doctrine  of 
the  great  antiquity  of  the  earth  ; 
for  out  of  the  expressly  scientific 
circles,  very  little — you  [viz.,  Count 
Adare]  are  aware  —  is  known  of 
what  scientific  men  are  about"  ! 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


107 


and  many  of  them  taught  there  for  many  years.1  It  was 
with  a  true  insight  into  the  higher  intellectual  needs  of 
the  nation  that  the  successive  Governments  of  the  Eevo- 


1  Before  the  age  of  the  Revolu- 
tion, which  did  so  much  to  pro- 
mote higher  scientific  education, 
Paris  possessed  already  many  great 
schools.  First  in  importance  was 
the  College  de  France,  founded  in 
1530  by  Francis  I.  Gassendi  and 
Roberval  taught  there  in  the 
seventeenth  century,  and  about 
the  middle  of  the  eighteenth  cen- 
tury science  began  to  be  more  ex- 
tensively represented,  Lalande  and 
Daubenton,  occupying  chairs.  The 
College  et  Ecole  de  Chirurgie  was  an 
ancient  establishment.  There  was 
the  Jardin  des  Plantes,  with  Buffon, 
Lemonnier,  ,Daubenton,  and  Four- 
croy  ;  the  Ecole  royale  des  Mines, 
founded  in  1783,  where  Duhamel 
taught  metallurgy ;  the  Ecole  des 
Fonts  et  Chausse"es,  founded  by 
Turgot  in  1775.  Daubenton,  Four- 
croy,  and  Vicq  d'Azyr  taught  in 
the  Ecole  vdteYiuaire  d'Alfort, 
founded  in  1766.  Besides  the 
Aeaddmie  des  Sciences,  the  Acade- 
mic royale  de  Chirurgie,  founded 
by  Lapeyronie  under  Louis  XV.  in 
1731,  had  a  great  influence  on  the 
development  of  anatomy  and  sur- 
gery during  the  eighteenth  century. 
Tenon  and  Petit,  as  well  as  Quesnay 
the  economist,  were  amongst  its 
members,  and  it  kept  up  a  lively 
intercourse  with  anatomists  all  over 
Europe.  The  Paris  academies  had 
also  their  representatives  and  con- 
nections in  the  provinces.  Inde- 
pendent academies  of  science  were 
affiliated  with  the  Academic  des  Sci- 
ences— 1716  at  Bordeaux,  1706  at 
Montpellier,  1746  at  Toulouse,  1766 
at  Be"ziers.  Before  having  received 
their  Icttrcs  patcntes,  which  gave 
their  members  certain  privileges, 
most  of  these  academies  had  exist- 
ed as  independent  societies.  Other 


provincial  academies,  such  as  Aries 
(1668),  Nimes  (1684),  Soissons 
(1674),  Marseilles  (1726),  were  affili- 
ated with  the  Academic  francaise. 
Others,  such  as  Caen  (1705),  Lyons 
(1724),  Dijon  (1740),  Rouen  (1744), 
Amiens  and  Nancy  (1750),  Besan- 
con  (1757),  Metz  (1760),  Clermont 
(1780),  Orleans  (1786),  were  not 
specially  affiliated.  These  dates 
show  how  very  much  earlier  a 
literary  and  scientific  organisation 
existed  in  France  than  in  other 
countries.  The  Protestant  univer- 
sities in  Germany  formed  an  or- 
ganisation of  a  different  kind,  with 
which  I  shall  deal  later  on.  The 
academic  system,  so  early  developed 
in  France,  was  of  great  use  to  the 
culture  of  the  sciences.  French 
science  is  usually  considered  to  be 
almost  entirely  located  in  Paris. 
M.  Bouillier  ('L'Institut  et  les 
Academies  de  Province,'  Paris, 
1879)  has  drawn  attention  to  the 
great  services  of  this  network  of 
academies.  Many  of  the  most  emi- 
nent writers  belonged  to  these  pro- 
vincial centres,  and  worked  for 
them  even  after  becoming  members 
of  the  more  celebrated  academies. 
Montesquieu  is  connected  with  Bor- 
deaux, Cassini  and  many  eminent 
doctors  with  Montpellier,  Dijon  has 
the  honour  of  bringing  out  Rous- 
seau, and  Toulouse  gave  prizes  to 
Bossut  and  Clairault.  Robespierre's 
name  is  connected  with  the  Academy 
of  Arras,  Marat  discourses  at  Rouen 
and  Lyons  on  electricity  and  optics, 
and  Dan  ton  and  Bonaparte  compete 
for  the  prix  Raynal  at  Lyons. 
"Mais,"  says  M.  Bouillier,  "ce  qui 
nous  semble  le  plus  digne  de 
remarque  et  d'eloge,  ce  sont  les 
ecoles  gratuites  de  dessin,  les  cours 
gratuits  de  physique,  de  chimie, 


108  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

lution,  in  the  midst  of  the  more  pressing  problems  of 
national  safety  and  welfare,  betook  themselves  to  the 
solution  of  the  great  problem  of  national  education  and 
the  instruction  of  all  grades  of  society.  "The  Convention," 
says  the  historian  of  public  instruction,1  "  affords  us  the 
strange  and  grand  spectacle  of  an  assembly,  which  on  the 
one  side  seems  to  have  no  other  mission  than  to  crush  in 
the  name  of  public  welfare  everything  that  stands  in  the 
17.  way  of  the  triumph  of  the  Republican  State,  and  which 

Promoted 

£y  Govern-  can  see  no  other  way  of  attaining  this  than  the  most 
Revolution,  terrible  and  cruel  of  tyrannies ;  and  which  on  the  other 
side  devotes  itself,  with  a  stoical  calm  and  serenity,  form- 
ing a  surprising  contrast  to  its  acts,  to  the  study,  the 
examination,  and  the  discussion  of  all  the  problems  in- 
volved in  public  instruction,  of  all  the  measures  con- 
ducive to  the  progress  of  science.  It  had  the  glory  of 
creating  institutions,  some  of  which  were  carried  away  by 
the  blast  of  the  Eevolution,  but  among  which  the  most 
important  still  exist  for  the  great  honour  of  France,  and 
bear  proof  of  the  lof  tiness  of  her  ideas." 2 

dliistoire     naturelle,     d'anatomie.  *  C.  Hippeau,  'L'lnstructionpub- 

d'antiquites,  fondes  par  un  certain  lique  en  France  pendant  la  Revolu- 

nombred'academieset.entreautres,  tion,'  le  seVie,  preface,  p.  xix. 

par  Dijon,  par  Rouen,  par  Bordeaux,  -  It  appears  nowadays  a  kind  of 

par  Toulouse,   par  Montpellier,  et  paradox  that,  as   M.    Hippeau   re- 

dont    lea    professeurs    e"taient    des  marks,  in  the  very  year  1 793,  when 

membres,    non    rdtribue's    de    ces  "  the    Convention    was    labouring 

academies.    ...     A  combien   de  with  a  feverish  ardour  at  the  crea- 

jeunes  talents  les  academies  provin-  tion  of  schools  of  all  degrees,"  this 

ciales  n'ont-elles  pas  donne  1'essor,  ;   same  Convention,  on  a  report  of  the 

par  leurs  recompenses  solennelles  et  Committee  of   Public   Instruction, 

leurs  encouragements  ?    Combien  de  voted  on  the   8th   of  August    the 

leurs  laureats  ne  sont  pas  devenus  suppression  of  all  the  academies  of 

des  hommes  celebres?"  (p.  81,  &c.)  j   Paris  and  the  provinces.     On  this 

Besides  Bouillier,  consult  on  these  i   M.  Bouillier('L'Institut  et  les  Aca- 

matters  the  several  articles,  "  Aca-  demies,'  p.  95)  remarks  :  "  Bientot 

demie,"  "College,"  "Ecole,"  in  the  !   il  est  vrai,  les  academies  devaient 

'  Grande  Encyclopedic.'  renaitre     apres     la    chute    de     la 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


109 


It  was  of  immense  importance  to  the  cause  of  science 
that  in  many  of  the  discussions  of  that  assembly  a 
marked  preference  was  shown  for  the  scientific  side  of 
instruction.  In  this  matter,  as  in  many  others,  the  suc- 
cessful constructive  efforts  of  the  Eevolutionary  Govern- 
ments came  from  the  side  of  those  brought  up  in  the 


Montagne  et  du  Comite  de  salut 
public.  Nous  n'ignorons  pas  que 
c'est  encore  la  Convention  qui,  prise 
d'un  tardif  remords,  la  veille  seule- 
ment  du  jour  ou  elle  devait  faire 
place  a  unautregouvernementmoins 
despotique  et  moins  cruel,  de"cre"ta 
1'organisation  de  1'Institut.  Mais 
la  Convention  du  3  brumaire  an 
iv.  n'etait  plus  celle  de  1793  ;  c'e"tait 
en  re'alite'  une  autre  Convention, 
e"puree,  de'cime'e,  renouvelee,  animee 
d'un  tout  autre  esprit,"  &c.,  &c. 
The  idea  of  a  national  Institute  for 
the  advancement  of  letters,  science, 
.and  arts  was  a  very  early  one  (see 
'  Eapport  de  Talleyrand  Perigord,' 
September  1791,  Hippeau,  p.  102). 
The  explanation  how  the  same 
Government  which  was  labouring  at 
the  problem  of  a  national  instruc- 
tion, crowned  by  the  higher  teaching 
and  research  of  an  Institute,  could 
begin  by  closing  the  existing  acad- 
emies and  universities,  lies  in  this, 
that  the  aim  was  to  make  education 
general  and  learning  popular,  not 
merely  fashionable,  as  it  had  been. 
See,  for  instance,  what  Ducos  said 
on  the  18th  December  1792  :  "  Les 
moeurs  d'un  peuple  corrompu  ne 
se  rdgenerent  point  par  de  legers 
adoucissements,  mais  par  de  vigour- 
euses  et  brusques  institutions.  II 
faut  opter  ouvertement  entre  1'edu- 
cation  domestique  et  la  liberte  ;  car 
citoyens,  tant  que  par  une  instruc- 
tion commune  vous  n'aurez  pas 
rapproche  le  pauvre  du  riche,  le 
faible  du  puissant ;  tant  que,  pour 
me  servir  des  expressions  de  Plu- 
iarque,  vous  n'aurez  pas  achemine  a 


une  ineme  trace,  et  moule  sur  une 
meme  forme  de  vertu  tous  les 
enfants  de  la  patrie,  c'est  en  vain 
que  vos  lois  proclamerout  la  sainte 
egalite,  la  Republique  sera  toujours 
divisee  en  deux  classes  :  les  citoyens 
et  les  messieurs"  (Hippeau,  2e 
serie,  p.  21).  It  was  because  the 
academies  and  colleges  supported 
"  les  messieurs "  that  they  were 
suppressed.  In  the  end  education 
must  always  begin  from  above,  and 
before  the  people  can  be  taught 
you  must  form  their  teachers.  See 
Lakanal's  Report  on  the  Ecoles  nor- 
males,  Hippeau,  vol.  i.  p.  408.  The 
academies  and  colleges  of  the  eigh- 
teenth century  were  closed  in  order 
to  make  room  for  that  uniform 
system  of  public  instruction  de- 
scribed by  Talleyrand  and  Condor- 
cet,  but  not  without  a  frequently 
expressed  admiration  for  the  work 
which  they  had  done.  See  the  de- 
fence of  the  academies  by  Condor- 
cet  (Hippeau,  loc.  cit.,  vol.  i.  p.  272), 
and  the  tribute  to  the  "College  de 
France,"  by  Gilbert  Romme  (ibid., 
vol.  i.  p.  308).  The  arguments  for 
radical  change  are  summed  up  by 
that  speaker  as  follows  :  ' '  L'exist- 
ence  de  ces  corps  privilege's  blesse 
tous  nos  principes  republicains, 
attaque  I'e'galite'  et  la  liberte  de 
penser  et  nuit  aux  progres  des 
arts.  Mais  si  leur  organisation  est 
vicieuse,  les  e'le'ments  en  sont  bons, 
et  nous  serviront  utilement  dans 
1'organisation  nouvelle  de  1'instruc- 
tion  publique  que  vous  allez  de"- 
creter"  (p.  309). 


110 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


18. 

Condorcet. 


school  of  Voltaire  and  the  Encyclopaedists,  whilst  the 
work  of  destruction  had  been  performed  by  the  followers 
of  Eousseau.  No  one  has  expressed  himself  on  the  value 
of  scientific  study  and  knowledge  in  a  clearer  or  more 
far-seeing  manner  than  Condorcet.  In  his  '  Eeport  and 
Project  of  a  Decree  on  the  General  Organisation  of  Public 
Instruction,'  which  he  presented  to  the  National  Assembly 
in  the  name  of  the  Committee  of  Public  Instruction, 
he  says : l  "  Many  motives  have  brought  about  the  kind 
of  preference  which  is  accorded  to  the  mathematical  and 
physical  sciences.  Firstly,  for  men  who  do  not  devote 
themselves  to  long  meditations,  who  do  not  fathom  any 
kind  of  knowledge — even  the  elementary  study  of  these 
sciences  is  the  surest  means  of  developing  their  intel- 
lectual faculties,  of  teaching  them  to  reason  rightly  and 
to  analyse  their  ideas.2  ...  It  is  because  in  the  natural 
sciences  the  ideas  are  more  simple,  more  rigorously  cir- 
cumscribed, it  is  because  their  language  is  more  perfect, 
&c.,  &c.  .  .  .  These  sciences  offer  a  remedy  for  prejudice, 
for  smallness  of  mind — a  remedy,  if  not  more  certain, 
at  least  more  universal,  than  philosophy  itself.3  .  .  .  Those 


1  It  was  presented  on  the  20th 
and  21st  April  1792.     See  Hippeau, 
le    serie,    pp.     185-288.       It    was 
printed  by  order  of  the  Convention, 
Paris,  Imprimerie  nationale,  1793. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  203. 

3  Ibid.,  p.  204.     It  is  interesting 
to  see  how  in  all  these  reports  the 
exact  sciences  are  placed  in  the  fore- 
ground.     See,   for  instance,   what 
Gilbert  Romrne  says  of  the  teaching 
of    the  proposed    institute:    "  Les 
sciences    mathematiques   et    phys- 
iques, morales  et  politiques,  1'agri- 
culture  et  les  arts  mecaniques,  la 
litterature  et  les  beaux-arts,  com- 


poseront  1'enseignement  des  insti- 
tuts  ou  Ton  pourra  suivre,  dans 
leurs  e'le'ments,  I'e'chelle  entiere  des 
connaissances  humaines  "  (vol.  i.  p. 
322).  "  Les  lycees  seront  1'ecole  des 
gens  instruits  ;  ils  embrasseront  les 
sciences,  les  arts  et  les  lettres  dans 
toute  leur  etendue."  One  is  forcibly 
reminded  that  the  most  perfect 
realisation  of  this  arrangement  of 
studies  is  to  be  found  a  century 
later  in  the  provincial  science  col- 
leges of  this  country.  The  prefer- 
ence, however,  is  now  given  to 
science  mainly  for  ultilitarian  rea- 
sons :  the  difference  is  shown  by 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN   FRANCE.  Ill 

who  follow  their  course,  see  the  coming  of  an  epoch 
when  the  practical  usefulness  of  their  application  will 
reach  greater  dimensions  than  were  ever  hoped  for,  when 
the  progress  of  the  physical  sciences  must  produce  a 
fortunate  revolution  in  the  arts.  And  lastly,  we  have 
yielded  to  the  general  tendency  of  men's  minds,  which 
in  Europe  seem  to  incline  towards  these  sciences  with 
an  ever-increasing  ardour.  .  .  .  Literature  has  its  limits,, 
the  sciences  of  observation  and  calculation  have  none. 
Below  a  certain  degree  of  talent,  the  taste  for  literary 
occupations  produces  either  ridiculous  pride  or  a  mean 
jealousy  towards  such  talents  as  one  cannot  attain.  In 
the  sciences,  on  the  contrary,  it  is  not  with  the  opinion 
of  men  but  with  nature  that  we  have  to  engage  in  a 
contest,  the  triumph  of  which  is  nearly  always  certain, 
where  every  victory  predicts  a  new  one." l 

"  It  is,"  says  Lakanal,  in  his  report  on  the  "  lilcoles  cen-        19. 

Lakanal. 

trales,"  16th  December  1794,  "of  great  importance  for 
the  nation  to  assure  itself  that  the  mathematical  sciences 
are  cultivated  and  deepened,  for  they  give  the  habit 
of  accuracy :  without  them  astronomy  and  navigation 
have  no  guide;  architecture,  both  civil  and  naval,  has 
no  rule ;  the  sciences  of  artillery  and  of  fortification  have 
no  foundation."  ~  Gradually,  under  the  pressure  of  exter- 


the  importance  then  attached  to 
mathematics  as  a  training  of  the 
intellect  in  precise  thinking ;  now- 
adays it  is  the  mechanical  side  that 
is  favoured,  and  this  is  only  too 
often  destructive  of  the  truly  scien- 
tific and  exact  spirit. 

1  Hippeau,  loc.  cit.,  p.  258.     Cf. 
p.  261  :   "  Batons  -  nous    .    .    .    de 


philosophic  et  la  me'thode  des  scien- 
ces physiques"  (Condorcet). 

"  Hippeau,  vol.  i.  p.  432.  It  is 
interesting  to  see  how  the  study  and 
teaching  of  the  sciences  in  course  of 
the  second  half  of  the  last  century 
in  France  undergo  a  development. 
The  literary  interest  predominates 
in  Fontenelle.  Buffou  and  Voltaire 


porter  dans  les  sciences  morales  la   i   add    to    it    the    philosophical    and 


112 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


nal  events,  the  exigencies  of  war  and  the  defence  of  the 
country  gain  the  upper  hand,  and  a  central  establishment 
is  founded  to  cultivate  and  teach  the  sciences  and  arts, 
"  upon  which  depend  the  defence  of  the  Republic  by  land 
and  sea." l  Few  of  the  higher  and  philanthropic  aims  of 
the  great  educational  leaders  of  the  early  years  of  the 
Eevolution — of  Mirabeau,  of  Talleyrand,  of  Condorcet — 
were  realised ;  little  was  done  for  primary  education ; 
but  science  can  boast  of  having  been  worthily  represented 
and  supported  in  the  two  great  schools  which  still  bear 
their  original  designation,  and  which  can  show  a  record 
of  celebrated  names  and  magnificent  work  superior  prob- 
ably to  that  of  any  other  similar  institution  in  Europe. 
They  are  the  "  Ecole  normale  superieure "  and  the 
male.  Ecole  "  Ecole  centrale  des  Travaux  publics,"  better  known  by 

polytech-  , 

the  title  "  Ecole  polytechnique."       The  founders  of  this 


philanthropic,  the  Encyclopaedists 
and  Condorcet  the  educational ;  the 
events  of  the  Revolution  and  the 
discussions  in  the  Assemblies  bring 
out  more  and  more  the  instructive, 
the  utilitarian,  and  the  economical 
aspects.  The  only  creations  which 
resulted  were  those  in  which  the 
latter  aims  were  predominant. 

1  Lakanal,  see   Hippeau,   vol.   i. 
p.  447." 

2  To  these  two  great  schools  must 
be  added  as  a  third  the  "Museum 
d'Histoire  naturelle,"  "  le  plus  mag- 
nifique  e"tablissement  que  les  scien- 
ces aient  posse"de"  (Cuvier,  "^Eloge 
de  Fourcroy,"  part  ii.  of  the  '  Eloges 
historiques,'  p.  44,  Strasbourg,  1819). 
The  foundation  of  the  "  Ecole  cen- 
trale  des  Travaux  publics  "  was  pro- 
posed by  Barere  on  the  llth  March 
1794,   and   definitely  organised  on 
the  report  of  Fourcroy  (Hippeau, 
vol.  i.  p.  446)  by  a  decree  of  7th  ven- 
ddmiaire,  an  iv.  (name  changed  to 


Ecole  poly  technique,  lothfructidor). 
The  opening  of  the  courses  was  an- 
nounced for  the  10th  frimaire  fol- 
lowing (Hippeau,  vol.  ii.  pp.  139, 174, 
175).  The  foundation  of  the  "  Ecoles 
normales  "  was  proposed  by  Barere 
(13th  prairial,  an  ii.),  and  decreed  on 
a  report  of  Lakanal  (Hippeau,  vol.  i. 
p.  423)  on  the  9th  brumaire,  an  iii. 
(30th  October  1794)  (ibid.,  vol.  ii.  p. 
179).  The  courses  opened  on  the  1st 
pluviose.  The  work  of  the  school 
was  distributed  as  follows  :  Mathe- 
matics, Lagrange  and  Laplace ; 
physics,  Haiiy;  descriptive  geome- 
try, Monge  ;  natural  history,  Dau- 
benton ;  chemistry,  Berthollet ;  agri- 
culture, Thouin ;  geography,  Buache 
and  Mentelle  ;  history,  Volney ; 
morals,  Bernardin  de  St  Pierre. 
(Hippeau,  vol.  ii.  p.  180,  where  also 
will  be  found  extracts  from  the 
'  Moniteur '  of  the  9th  pluviose  on 
the  opening  addresses. )  The  oldest 
pupil  was  Bougainville,  the  great 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


113 


magnificent  institution  recognised  "  that,  in  spite  of  the 
diversity  of  applications,  mathematics  and  physics  are 
the  indispensable  basis  of  the  studies  in  view." 1  Though 
the  first  period  of  the  life  of  the  ]£cole  normale  only 
counted  four  months,2  we  are  indebted  to  it  for  the 


traveller.  The  Ecole  polytechnique 
received  an  allocation  of  £12,000, 
and  had  400  pupils  to  start  with. 
On  the  20th  frimaire,  an  iii.,  the 
Convention,  on  a  report  of  Thibau- 
deau,  voted  the  necessary  expenses 
for  the  enlargement  of  the  Museum 
d'Histoire  naturelle  (Hippeau,  vol. 
ii.  p.  196),— viz.,  nearly  £8000  for 
expenses,  and  £200  for  each  of  the 
professors.  The  Museum  had  been 
originally  destined  for  the  culture 
of  medicinal  plants.  Tournefort  had 
given  a  great  impetus  to  botanical, 
and  Buffon,  with  Daubenton,  to 
zoological  studies.  The  Convention 
added  several  to  the  courses  regu- 
larly held  there  on  natural  history, 
botany,  mineralogy,  and  general 
chemistry.  "  Ces  cours,"  says  Thi- 
baudeau,  "fournissent  500  lemons 
par  an,  offrent  I'ensemble  le  plus 
vaste  et  le  plus  complet  d'enseigne- 
ment  sur  toutes  les  branches  d'his- 
toire  naturelle  dont  le  plus  grand 
nombre  manquaient  totalement  a  la 
France  et  dont  quelques-unes  man- 
quent  encore  a  1'Europe,  1'applica- 
tion  immediate  de  toutes  les  sciences 
naturelles  au  commerce  et  aux  arts." 
Of  other  scientific  and  teaching 
institutions  I  must  mention  the 
"Bureau  des  Longitudes."  This 
was  organised  by  the  Convention 
on  a  discourse  by  Gre"goire,  7th 
messidor,  an  iii.  (24th  June  1795), 
in  which  he  refers  to  the  British 
Board  of  Longitude  and  the  superi- 
ority of  the  British  navy  (Hippeau, 
vol.  ii.  p.  219).  The  appointments  to 
this  bureau  were  the  gtometrcs  La- 
grange  and  Laplace,  the  astronomcs 
Lalande,  Cassini,  Mechain,  De- 

VOL.  I. 


lambre,  one  of  whom  had  to  deliver 
a  course  of  astronomy,  the  travellers 
Borda,  Bougainville,  the  gtographe 
Buache,  and  the  artist  Carocher. 
It  had  charge  of  the  observatory, 
which  had  already  been  reorganised 
by  a  decree  promoted  by  Lakaual  on 
the  31st  August  1793  (Hippeau,  vol. 
ii.  p.  76),  and  published  in  the  '  Con- 
naissance  des  Temps. '  There  were, 
besides,  several  military  schools  and 
the  medical  schools,  not  to  mention 
other  foundations  less  connected 
with  our  subject  but  equally  im- 
portant, such  as  the  School  of 
Oriental  Languages,  established  in 
the  Bibliotheque  nationale  (ger- 
minal,, an  iii.,  Hippeau,  vol.  ii.  p.  215) ; 
the  Ecoles  de  Saute",  established 
1 4th  frimaire,  an  iii.,  on  a  report  of 
Fourcroy,  in  Paris,  Strasbourg,  and 
Montpellier  (Hippeau,  vol.  ii.  p.  194). 

1  Ibid.,, vol.  i.  p.  450. 

2  The  Ecole  normale  was  closed 
on   the  30th  floreal,  an  iii.,   on  a 
decree    of    the    Convention    dated 
the  7th  of   that  month.      Danton 
explained  that  the  school  had  not 
taken  the  line  which  the  Conven- 
tion had  marked  out — the  courses 
in  general  having  offered  a  direct 
teaching    of    the    sciences    rather 
than  an  exposition  of  the  methods 
which  are  to  be  adopted  in  teaching 
(Hippeau,  vol.  ii.  p.  215).     It  also 
seems  that  the  eminent  teachers  of 
this  institution  had  few  pupils  suffi- 
ciently, prepared   to   follow   them. 
The    Ecole  normale  was  reopened 
in  the  year  1808  under  the  Empire, 
by  the  same  decree  of  17th  March 
which  organised  the  University  of 
France. 

H 


114 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


si.        foundation  of  a  new  branch  of  science — the  '  Descriptive 
Wamgft 
•Descriptive  Geometry '   of  Monge,   which  was   given   to   the  world 

through  shorthand  notes l  from  his  lectures  delivered  in 
that  institution.  They  form  the  beginning  of  the  new 
science,  since  developed  by  Poncelet,  Steiner,  and  others, 
and  known  under  the  name  of  "  protective  geometry/'  - 

Next  to  mathematics  with  its  analytical  and  graphical 
application  to  physics  and  the  arts,  the  subject  most  culti- 
vated in  these  higher  educational  establishments  of  Paris 
at  the  end  of  the  last  century  was  the  new  science  of 
chemistry.  With  some  justice  this  science  has  been  termed 
a  French  science,3  not  so  much  because  even  at  that  time 


82. 
Science  of 


1  See  the  account  of  the  origin  of 
this  branch  of  mathematics  in  Brig- 
son's  edition  of  the  '  Geome"trie  de- 
scriptive,' Paris,  1847.  In  the  pro- 
gramme prefixed  to  the  treatise  the 
three  aspects  of  the  new  school — 
the  national,  the  practical,  and  the 
educational — are  well  set  forth  : 
"  Pour  tirer  la  nation  franeaise  de 
la  dependance  ou  elle  a  ete  jusqu'a 
present  de  I'industrie  etrangere,  il 
faut  premierement  diriger  1'educa- 
tion  nationale  vers  la  connaissance 
des  objets  qui  exigent  de  1'exacti- 
tude.  .  .  .  H  faut,  en  second  lieu, 
rendre  populaire  la  connaissance  d'un 
grand  nombre  de  phenomenes  natu- 
rela.  ...  La  geometric  descriptive 
est  un  moyen  de  rechercher  la  ver- 
ite" ;  elle  offre  des  exemples  perpe"- 
tuels  du  passage  du  connu  a  1'incon- 
nu  ;  et  parcequ'elle  est  toujours  ap- 
pliquee  a  des  objets  susceptibles  de 
la  plus  grande  evidence,  il  est  neces- 
saire  de  la  faire  entrer  dans  le  plan 
d'une  education  nationale/'  Monge 
generalised  and  placed  on  a  scien- 
tific basis  the  methods  used  pre- 
viously by  carpenters  and  stone- 
cutters, and  partially  dealt  with 
geometrically  by  Courcier,  Derand, 
Mathurin,  Jous.se.  and  Frezier.  See 


Montucla,  '  Hiatoire  des  Mathema- 
tiques,'  vol.  iii.  p.  15. 

2  Monge  taught  also  at  the  Ecole 
polytechnique  from  the  beginning. 

|  See  the  remarks  of  Chasles  ('Rap- 
port sur  les  Progres  de  hi  Geo- 
metric,' Paris,  1870,  p.  2):  "L'en- 
seignement  theorique  et  profond 
qui  a  ete  la  base  de  la  premiere  et 
judicieuse  organisation  de  ce  grand 
etablissement  etait  eminemment 
favorable  aux  progres  de  la  science, 
en  meme  temps  qu'il  preparait  seri- 
eusement  les  eleves  a  Fentree  dans 
les  ecoles  d'application. "  The  au- 
thor then  refers  with  regret  to  the 
less  scientific  tone  which  had  crept 
into  the  studies  of  that  great  school 
in  the  course  of  this  century.  See 
also  p.  379. 

3  A.Wurtz  ('Histoire  des  Doctrines 
chimiques,'  Paris,  1868,  p.  1) :  "La 
chimie  est   une  science  francaise  ; 
elle  fut  constituee  par  Lavoisier." 
Cf.  Dumas  ( '  Lecons  sur  la  Philoso- 
phic chimique,'  Paris,  1837,  p.  137). 
Buckle  (' History  of  Civilisation,' &c., 
3  vols.,  vol.  ii.  p.  366,  London,  1866) 
says  :  ' '  That  we  owe  to  France  the 
existence  of  chemistry  as  a  science 
will  be  admitted  by  every  one  who 
uses  the  word  science  in  the  sense 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


115 


chemistry  was  not  indebted  to  illustrious  foreigners l  for 
some  of  its  most  important  discoveries,  as  because  the 
modern  scientific  spirit  of  accurate  measurement  first  took 
hold  of  chemical  phenomena  on  a  large  scale  in  the  many 
important  investigations  which  bear  the  name  of  Lavoi- 
sier and  his  followers,  through  whom  the  great  reform  of 
modern  chemical  knowledge  and  research  was  permanently 
established.  It  has  been  significantly  pointed  out 2  that  it 
was  the  union  of  mathematical  with  empirical  knowledge 
which,  through  men  like  Laplace,  Meusnier,  Monge,  first 


in  which  alone  it  ought  to  be  un- 
derstood, &c.  .  .  .  Until  Lavoisier 
entered  the  field  there  were  no  gen- 
eralisations wide  enough  to  entitle 
chemistry  to  be  called  a  science." 
The  correctness  of  this  view  is  fully 
and  impartially  examined  by  Her- 
mann Kopp  ('  Die  Entwickelung  der 
Chemie  in  der  neueren  Zeit,'  Miin- 
chen.  1873,  p.  89,  &c.)  He  fully 
upholds  the  claims  of  Lavoisier  to 
be  called  the  father  of  modern 
chemistry  (p.  145).  See  also  what 
Liebig  says. 

1  These  were  mainly,  Black  (dis- 
covered carbonic  acid,  called  fixed 
air,  in  1754),  Cavendish  (discovered 
hydrogen  or  inflammable  air  in 
1767),  and  Priestley,  who  between 
1771  and  1774  discovered  oxy- 
gen (dephlogisticated  air),  nitrogen 
(phlogisticated  air),  and  several  of 
its  compounds,  among  them  am- 
monia (alkaline  air).  Of  Priestley 
it  is  said  by  Cuvier  that  he  may 
well  be  considered  as  one  of  the 
fathers  of  modern  chemistry,  "  mais 
c'est  un  pore  qui  ne  voulut  jamais 
reconnaitre  sa  nlle  "  ('  Eloges,'  vol.  i. 
p.  208).  Elsewhere  ('  Rapport  his- 
torique  sur  les  Progres  des  Sciences 
naturelles,'  Paris,  1810,  p.  90)  Cu- 
vier dates  the  revolution  in  chem- 
istry from  the  introduction  of  the 
mathematical  spirit :  "  II  en  est 


une  cause  encore  plus  essentielle  a 
laquelle  meme  on  doit  a  proprement 
parler,  et  cette  theorie  nouvelle,  et 
les  decouvertes  qui  1'ont  fait  naitre. 
.  .  .  C'est  1'esprit  mathe"matique 
qui  s'est  introduit  dans  la  science 
et  la  rigoureuse  precision  qu'on  a 
porte'e  dans  1'examen  de  toutes  ses 
operations.  .  .  .  C'est  dans  le 
Traite  elementaire  de  Lavoisier  que 
1'Europe  vit  pour  la  premiere  fois 
avec  etonnement  le  systeme  entier 
de  la  nouvelle  chimie,"  &c. 

2  Kopp,  loc.  cit.,  p.  202:  "In- 
deed, if  we  look  at  those  who  first 
worked  together  with  Lavoisier  or 
in  his  spirit,  we  shall  find  such  as 
had  devoted  themselves  principally 
to  mathematics  or  mathematical 
physics,  men  like  Laplace,  Meus- 
nier, Monge.  Among  chemists  La- 
voisier stood  for  a  long  time  almost 
alone  in  his  opinions."  This  view 
is  also  taken  by  Cuvier  ('  Rapport,' 
p.  91):  "Les  nouveaux  chimistes 
francais  .  .  .  ont  eu  a  se  louer  du 
concours  de  quelques-uns  de  nos 
geometres  les  plus  distingues,"  &c. ; 
and  he  attributes  the  next  great 
step  in  chemical  science  to  a  similar 
introduction  of  a  "  rigueur  toute 
mathematique  "  ('Rapport  sur  la 
Chimie  lu  a  la  Seance  des  4  Acad.,' 
23rd  April  1826). 


sciences. 


116  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

brought  about  the  general  recognition  of  Lavoisier's  ideas  : 
whereas  the  more  exclusive  representatives  of  chemistry, 
such  as  Berthollet  and  Guyton,  held  aloof  for  some  con- 
siderable time.  In  the  earlier  syllabus  of  the  £cole 
polytechnique,  chemistry  was  brought  into  a  similar 
proximity  with  the  mathematical  branches.  And  Ber- 
thollet's  '  Statique  chimique  '  denotes  by  its  title  alone 
the  mathematical  spirit  in  which  the  work  was  conceived. 
as.  About  that  time  also  two  new  sciences  were,  if  not 

New  ma  the-    .  .       .       .  .  .  ,       . 

invented,  at  least  set  on  a  farm  basis,  by  wmcn  the  use 
of  mathematics  was  very  largely  extended,  and  by  which 
great  realms  of  interesting  facts  were  made  accessible  to 
accurate  measurements  and  exact  reasoning.  Both  these 
sciences  can  be  claimed  by  France  as  almost  exclusively 
zt  her  own  creations.  They  are  the  science  of  crvstallo- 

Ciystallo- 

graphy  and  the  great  theory  of  probabilities.  The  former 
was  the  work  of  the  Abbe  Haiiy  ;  the  latter  formed,  next 
to  the  mechanics  of  the  heavens,  the  main  original  con- 
tribution by  which  Laplace  has  perpetuated  his  name  in 
the  history  of  science.  The  theory  of  the  Abbe  Haliy, 
who  first  taught  how  crystals  are  built  up  from  small 
particles  of  definite  and  regular  geometrical  forms,  such  as 
cubes,  pyramids,  &c.,  came  to  the  aid  of  the  mineralogists, 
who  before  him  had  vainly  groped  in  the  dark,  searching 
for  some  method  by  which  order  and  system  could  be 
introduced  into  the  lifeless  forms  of  nature  as  by  the 
methods  of  Linnaeus  and  Jussieu  it  had  been  introduced 
into  the  world  of  plants  and  animals.  Before  Haiiy, 
the  doctrines  of  mineralogy  had  been  either  attached  to 
geology  —  especially  in  the  celebrated  school  of  AVerner, 
or  latterly,  after  the  great  developments  in  chemistry  had 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


117 


set  in,  to  chemistry — especially  by  Bergmann.1  Haiiy 
established  the  science  of  minerals  on  an  independent 
foundation  by  studying  and  systematising  the  forms  of 
their  crystallisation ;  and  he  brought  the  science  of  min- 
eralogy from  Sweden  and  Germany  into  France,  and  gave 
it  an  independent  position.  Thus  it  came  to  form  a  con- 
necting-link between  the  mathematical — i.e.,  the  measur- 
ing and  calculating — and  the  purely  descriptive  sciences. 
"  Mineralogy,  though  it  is  that  part  of  natural  science 
which  deals  with  the  least  complicated  objects,  is  never- 
theless also  that  which  lends  itself  least  to  a  rational 
classification.  The  first  observers  named  the  minerals 
vaguely  according  to  their  external  appearances  and  their 
use.  It  was  not  until  the  middle  of  the  eighteenth 
century  that  it  was  attempted  to  subject  them  to  those 
methods  which  had  done  service  to  geology  and  botany  : 
the  hope  existed  of  establishing  among  them  genera  and 


1  See  an  account  of  the  work  of 
the  chemical  school,  to  which  Cron- 
sted  (the  inventor  of  the  blow-pipe), 
Berginann,  Kirwan,  and  Klaproth 
belonged,  in  Cuvier's  '  Rapport '  (p. 
163).  Also  his  "  Eloge  de  Haiiy  " 
('Eloges  histor.,'  vol.  iii.  p.  143,  &c.) 
The  beginnings  of  geometrical  crys- 
tallography seem  to  go  back  to  Lin- 
naeus ;  but  his  view  was  discouraged 
in  France  by  Buffon,  who  disliked 
Linnseus's  writings.  Whewell,  who 
was  himself  an  authority  on  crys- 
tallography, thinks  Rome'  de  1'Isle, 
who  was  not  an  Academician,  had 
only  scant  justice  done  to  him  by 
Haiiy  and  his  friends  ('  Hist,  of 
the  Induct.  Sciences,'  3rd  ed.,  vol. 
iii.  p.  176).  More  recent  writers, 
such  as  Kobell  ('  Geschichte  der 
Mineralogie,'  Miinchen,  1864,  p.  73, 
&c. )  and  Nicol  (article  ' '  Crystal- 


lography," '  Ency.  Brit.'),  have  done 
him  justice.  The  'Grande  Ency- 
clopedic '  thus  summarises  the  work 
of  Rome"  de  1'Isle :  "  II  mesura 
mecaniquement  [viz.,  with  Caran- 
geot's  goniometer]  les  angles  et 
etablit  que  ces  angles  ont  toujours 
une  valeur  constante  dans  une 
meme  espece  mineral ogique."  That 
of  Haiiy  is  summarised  in  the  two 
laws  :  "  1°,  Tous  les  elements  sem- 
blables  d'un  cristal  sont  toujours 
semblablement  et  simultane"ment 
modifies  (loi  de  syme'trie) ;  2°,  toute 
facette  modifiante  intercepte  sur 
les  aretes  de  la  figure  primitive 
des  longueurs  proportionelles  a  des 
multiples  simples  de  la  longueur 
de  ces  aretes  (loi  de  derivation)" 
(Berthelot  in  '  Grande  Encyclop.,' 
vol.  xiii.  p.  397). 


118 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


species,  as  among  organised  beings,  and  it  was  forgot- 
ten that  in  mineralogy  the  principle  is  absent  which 
had  given  birth  to  the  idea  of  species — viz.,  that  of 
generation.  The  principle  of  individuality,  such  as  it  is 
conceived  in  the  organic  world — viz.,  the  unity  of  action 
of  different  organs  which  co-operate  in  the  preservation  of 
the  same  life — can  scarcely  be  admitted  in  mineralogy."1 
The  Abb4  Haiiy,  by  founding  the  science  of  minerals 
on  their  regular  forms  of  crystallisation,  made  mineralogy 
"  as  precise  and  methodical  as  astronomy ;  in  fact,  we 
can  say  in  one  word  that  he  was  to  Werner2  and  Rome 
de  1'Isle,  his  predecessors,  what  Newton  had  been  to 
Kepler  and  Copernicus."3 
25.  From  that  well-defined  province  of  science  which  deals 

Theory  of 

Probability.  in  a  precise  and  strict  manner  with  the  simple  numerical 
relations  which  seem  to  underlie  all  forms  of  movement 
in  nature,  be  they  on  a  stupendous  or  on  a  minute  scale 


1  Cuvier,  "  Eloge  de  Haiiy"   in 
'  Eloges  historiques,'  vol.  iii.  p.  155. 

2  The  character  of  Werner  (1750- 
1815)    is    nowhere    better ,  painted 
than  by  Cuvier  in  his  "Eloge   de 
Werner"  (loc.  cit.,  vol.  ii.  p.  303,  &c.) 
"  II  commence  1'epoque  la  plus  re- 
marquable  de  la  science  de  la  terre, 
et  meme  Ton   peut  dire  qu'a  lui 
seul   il  la  remplit.    ...    II  s'est 
forme  des  academies  entieres,   qui 
ont  pris  son  noin"   (for  instance, 
the  Edinburgh  Wernerian  Society, 
founded  by   Jameson,    1808-1859), 
"comme  si  elles  eussent  voulu  in- 
voquer  son  genie  et  s'en  faire  un 
patron  d'une  espece  auparavant  in- 
connue.    Qui  ne  croirait,  a  entendre 
parler  de  succes  si  peu  ordinaires, 
que  ce  fut  quelqu'un  de  ces  hommes 
ardens  a   propager   leur    doctrine, 
qui  par  des  ouvrages  nombreux  et 


eloquens,  ont  subjugue  leurs  con- 
temporains,  ou  qui  se  sont  procure 
des  partisans  par  1'ascendant  d'une 
grande  richesse  ou  d;une  position 
elevee  dans  1'ordre  social  ?  Rien  de 
tout  cela  :  confine  dans  une  petite 
ville  de  Saxe,  sans  autorite  dans 
son  pays,  il  n'avait  aucune  influence 
sur  la  fortune  de  ses  disciples  ;  il 
n'entretenait  point  de  liaisons  avec 
des  personnes  eu  place :  d'un  nat- 
urel  singulierement  tiuride,  hesitant 
toujours  a  ecrire,  a  peine  subsiste- 
t-il  de  lui  quelques  feuilles  d'im- 
pression.  .  .  .  C'est  ainsi  qu'en 
peu  d'annees  la  petite  ecole  de 
Freyberg.  destinee  seulement.  dans 
le  principe,  h  former  quelques 
mineurs  pour  la  Saxe,  renouvela 
le  spectacle  des  premieres  univer- 
sites  du  moyen  age,"  &c.,  &c. 
3  Cuvier,  ibid.,  p.  163. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN    FRANCE.  119 

•i.e.,  from  the  province  of  mechanics  and  astronomy — 
two  different  roads  lead  into  those  extensive  domains  in 
which,  not  simplicity  and  regularity,  but  endless  variety 
and  complication,  seem  to  be  the  order  and  the  rule  of 
Life.  Even  a  century  ago  the  contrast  must  have  been 
striking  between  the  'Priiicipia '  of  Newton  and  the  '  Ex- 
position du  Systeme  du  Monde '  of  Laplace  on  the  one 
side,  and  the  great  array  of  volumes  of  Linnaeus,  Buffon, 
Jussieu,  Cuvier,  and  Lacepede  on  the  other ;  though  these 
after  all  embraced  only  a  small  portion  of  the  living  forms 
of  nature  which  they  attempted  to  classify  or  to  describe.1 
I  have  pointed  out  how  the  new  and  especially  the 
French  methods  of  chemistry  and  crystallography  con- 
quered a  large  portion  of  intermediate  ground,  subjected 
many  tangled  phenomena  to  exact  treatment,  and  pushed 
the  mathematical  method  far  into  the  dominion  of  natural 
history.  It  is  that  other  history,  not  natural,  but  human 
and  often  unnatural,  which  presents  the  opposite  extreme 
of  the  great  panorama  of  world-life.  It  is  significant 
that  almost  at  the  same  time  that  mathematical  reason- 
ing found  its  way  into  natural  history,  conquering  an  ex- 
tensive province  of  its  vast  territory,  an  entirely  different 
method  was  invented  with  the  aim  of  dealing  in  a  still 
more  vigorous  manner  with  the  phenomena  of  human 
life  and  society.  This  was  the  science  of  statistics,  and 


1  Cuvier  gives  some  figures  as  to 
the  increase  of  the  known  species 
•during  his  own  lifetime.  Lacepede 
had  described  about  1200  or  1300 


Linnaeus  had  counted  in  1778  about 
8000  species  of  plants.  Cuvier  in 
1824  estimates  the  number  as 
50,000  or  more  (see  '  Eloges,'  vol.  iii. 


distinct  species  of  fishes  ;  but  when  j    p.  469,  &c.,  where  he  also  gives  some 

Cuvier    pronounced    his   Eloge    in  idea    of    the    numbers    of    known 

1826,  the  Cabinet  du  Roi  contained  species  in  the  different  classes   of 

already    more    than    5000    species  •   animals). 

{'  Eloges  historiques,'  vol.  iii.  p.  317).  I 


120 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


connected  with  it  the  doctrine  of  averages  and  the  mathe- 
matical theory  of  probabilities.1     The  same  great  mind 


1  The  beginnings  of  the  science 
and  theory  of  probabilities  are  net 
subject  to  controversy,  as  were 
those  of  the  infinitesimal  calculus. 
Pascal  and  Fennat  about  the  middle 
of  the  seventeenth  century  entered 
into  a  correspondence  relative  to  a 
question  in  a  game  of  chance,  pro- 
pounded by  the  Chevalier  de  Mere", 
a  noted  gambler.  They  agreed  in 
their  answer,  but  could  not  con- 
vince their  friend,  who  moreover 
made  this  the  occasion  of  denounc- 
ing the  results  of  science  and  arith- 
metic. But  this  comparatively  in- 
significant problem  —  so  different 
from  the  great  cosmical  problems 
which  led  to  the  invention  of  the 
infinitesimal  calculus  about  the 
same  time  —  was  the  origin  of  a 
series  of  investigations  and  discus- 
sions in  which  the  greatest  mathe- 
maticians, such  as  Huygens,  James 
and  Daniel  Bernoulli,  De  Moivre, 
D'Alembert,  and  Condorcet  joined. 
Most  of  them  did  not  escape  the 
errors  and  misstatements  which 
creep  in  an  insidious  manner  into 
the  discussion  and  vitiate  the  conclu- 
sions. In  fact,  the  science  advanced 
through  the  influence  of  those  who 
depreciated  it  like  D'Alembert,  and 
those  who  exaggerated  its  import- 
ance like  Condorcet.  At  length, 
under  the  hands  of  Laplace,  who 
defined  it  as  common-sense  put  into 
figures  and  attributed  to  it  a  high 
educational  value,  it  assumed  a  state 
wellnigh  approaching  to  that  per- 
fection which  Euclid  gave  to  geo- 
metry and  Aristotle  to  logic.  Since 
the  publication  of  Laplace's  cele- 
brated '  Theorie  analytique  des  Pro- 
babiliteV  (Paris,  1812)  writers  on 
the  subject  have  found  ample  oc- 
cupation in  commenting  on  the 
theorems  or  recasting  the  proofs 
given  in  that  work,  which  holds  a 
similar  position  to  that  occupied  in 


!  another  department  of  mathematics 
by  the  'Disquisitiones  Arithmetics? ' 
of  Gauss  (1801).  Up  to  the  pres- 

;  ent  day  there  exist  differences  of 
opinion  as  to  the  value  of  the 
science,  the  two  opposite  views  be- 
ing represented  in  this  country  by 
Mill  ('Logic,'  5th  ed.,  vol.  ii.  p."  62) 
and  Jevons  ('  Principles  of  Science,' 
vol.  i. ),  the  latter  summing  up  his 
opinion  as  follows  :  "  In  spite  of  its 
immense  difficulties  of  application, 
and  the  aspersions  which  have  been 
mistakenly  cast  upon  it,  the  theory 
of  probabilities  is  the  noblest,  as  it 
will  in  course  of  time  prove  perhaps 
the  most  fruitful,  branch  of  mathe- 
matical science.  It  is  the  very 
guide  of  life,  and  hardly  can  we 
take  a  step  or  make  a  decision  of 
any  kind  without  correctly  or  in- 
correctly making  an  estimation  of 
probability"  (1st  ed.,  p.  248).  A 
similar  opinion  seems  to  have  been 
held  by  James  Clerk  Maxwell  (see 
Life  by  Campbell  and  Garnett,  p. 
143),  who  called  the  calculus  of 
probabilities  "  Mathematics  for 
practical  men."  In  this  country 
A.  de  Morgan  and  Todhunter,  the 
former  in  a  popular  essay  in  the 
1  Cabinet  Cyclopaedia '  and  in  a 
profound  treatise  in  the  '  Encyclo- 
paedia Metro politana,'  the  latter  in 
his  well  -  known  History  (London 
and  Cambridge,  1865),  have  done 
a  great  deal  to  make  this  subject 
better  understood.  The  applica- 
tions of  the  theory  have  gradually 
increased  through  numerous  mor- 
tality and  insurance  calculations ; 
as  also  in  the  estimations  of  error 
in  astronomical  and  physical  ob- 
servations, where  the  well-known 
method  of  least  squares  (first  em- 
ployed by  Gau.*s  in  1795,  see  Gauss, 
Werke,  vol.  vii.  p.  242  ;  first  pub- 
lished by  Legendre  in  1806,  and  then 
proved  by  Laplace  in  his  '  Theorie,' 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE.  121 

which  elaborated  the  principles  of  Newton  into  a  system 
of  the  universe,  and  attacked  the  intricate  mathematical 
problem  which  this  system  presented,  gave  to  the  world 
likewise  the  first  complete  treatise  on  that  calculus  which 
comes  into  play  if  we  eliminate  from  the  apparently  most 
arbitrary  region  of  phenomena,  that  of  human  life  and 
history,  all  regard  for  final  or  efficient  causes,  for  provi- 
dential design  and  freewill,  for  human  error,  human  malice 
and  benevolence — in  fact,  all  notice  of  that  element  which 
from  another  and  equally  important  point  of  view  forms 
the  subject  of  greatest  interest — the  inner  life  of  the  in- 
dividual. It  was  proposed,  and  it  has  since  been  carried 
out,  to  look  upon  human  beings  and  human  events  not  as 
things  possessed  of  an  inner  world  of  thought  and  freewill, 
but  as  lifeless  units,  more  uniform  and  regular  than  the 
balls  thrown  into  the  urn  at  an  election,  or  the  counters 
in  a  game  of  chance.  By  overstepping  with  one  bound 
the  great  field  of  human  activity,  full  of  so  much  con- 
fusion and  so  much  interest,  it  was  proposed  to  investi- 
gate what  knowledge  would  result  from  a  purely  mathe- 
matical inspection,  in  which  human  beings  figured  merely 
as  units  and  symbols.1  This  attempt,  which  has  since 


&c.,  1812)  is  now  extensively  em- 
ployed. Of  this  branch  of  mathe- 
matics Bertrand  says  :  "  Les  plus 
grands  geometres  ont  e"crit  sur  le 
calcul  des  probabilites ;  presque 
tous  ont  commis  des  erreurs :  la 
cause  en  est,  le  plus  souvent,  au 
de"sir  d'appliquer  des  principes  a 
des  problcmes  qui  par  leur  nature 
dchappent  a  la  science."  In  the 
hands  of  Clerk  Maxwell  the  cal- 
culus has  acquired  an  additional 
interest  and  importance  through 
the  distinction  which  he  made  be- 
tween what  he  termed  the  "histori- 


cal" and  the  "statistical  method" 
of  treating  phenomena,  and  the 
application  of  the  latter  to  the 
kinetic  theory  of  gases  (see  Life, 
pp.  438,  562).  This  subject  will 
occupy  our  attention  in  a  special 
chapter. 

1  The  beginnings  of  the  science  of 
statistics  belong  likewise  to  the  age 
that  produced  the  higher  mathema- 
tics. More  extensive  "countings"' 
seem  to  have  been  contemporaneous 
with  more  refined  calculations.  Her- 
mann Conring,  professor  at  Helm- 
stiidt,  a  friend  of  Leibniz  (see  Leib- 


122 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


led  to  such  interesting  results,  and  which  has  furnished 
almost  all  the  knowledge  upon  which  a  judicious  regula- 
tion and  government  of  society  depends,  was  the  work  of 
Laplace,  and  was  produced  in  an  age  and  in  a  nation 
which  seemed  to  have  set  at  naught  all  ideas  of  order  and 
method  in  human  affairs,  which  defied  all  authority  and 
all  tradition,  and  trusted  its  fate  to  the  most  radical 
revolution  which  civilised  society  ever  witnessed.1 

It  is  curious  to  read  the  criticism  which  the  first 
Napoleon,  that  wayward  child  of  the  Eevolution,  passed 
on  the  author  of  the  mechanics  of  the  heavens  and  the 
theory  of  probability.  Laplace,  like  so  many  other  men 
of  science,  had  been  called  by  the  Emperor  to  assist  in 
the  labours  of  administration,  but,  according  to  his  judg- 
ment, proved  himself  a  poor  administrator,  being  unable 


niz's  '  Philosophische  Schriften,'  ed. 
Gerhardt,  vol.  i.  p.  155),  lectured 
about  1660  on  subjects  now  com- 
prised under  the  term  "  Statistics," 
and  about  thesame  time  John  Graunt 
of  London  published  '  Natural  and 
Political  Annotations  made  upon 
the  Bills  of  Mortality '  (1666).  Sir 
William  Petty,  one  of  the  founders 
•of  the  Royal  Society,  published  in 
1683  'Five  Essays  in  Political 
Arithmetick.'  The  newly  discov- 
ered calculus  of  probabilities  in- 
duced mathematicians  to  take  an  in- 
terest in  the  subject,  and  to  urge  the 
desirability  of  gaining  data  for  their 
•calculations.  Many  of  these  turned 
upon  questions  of  mortality  and 
the  ravages  of  diseases,  such  as  the 
.smallpox.  But  though  undoubt- 
edly the  fact  that  during  the 
French  Revolution  mathematicians 
•for  the  first  time  had  a  great  in- 
fluence in  administrative  and  gov- 
ernmental matters  contributed 
enormously  to  the  introduction  of 
statistical  methods,  the  great  epoch 


in  this  science  is  allied  with  the 
name  of  the  Belgian  Quetelet 
(1796-1874),  of  whom  more  later 
on. 

1  Cantor  ('  Historische  Notizen 
iiber  die  \Vahrscheinlichkeitsrech- 
nung,'  Halle,  1874,  p.  6)  says : 
"  The  tendency  of  thought  which 
prepared  the  Revolution,  and  which 
is  marked  by  an  unsparing  and  de- 
structive criticism  of  the  conditions 
of  society  in  state  and  family,  could 
not  dispense  with  an  instrument 
which,  more  than  any  other,  enables 
one  to  subject  to  general  views  the 
most  different  factors  of  civilisation. 
It  belonged  to  the  favourite  ideas  of 
that  age,  that  the  calculus  of  proba- 
bilities should  be  among  the  most 
important  subjects  of  public  in- 
struction ;  for  it  was  said  to  be  the 
calculus  of  common-sense,  through 
which  alone  the  influence  of  hope, 
fear,  and  emotion  on  our  judgment 
could  be  destroyed,  and  prejudice 
and  superstition  removed  from  the 
decisions  of  social  life. " 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE.  123 

to  grasp  practical  issues,  and  always  descending  into  in- 
finitesimals. It  is  hardly  to  be  doubted  now,  after  the 
lapse  of  a  century,  that  the  infinitesimals  of  Laplace  play 
a  more  important  part  in  problems  of  administration  and 
government  than  the  ideas  of  Napoleon.  Laplace,  un- 
like some  other  great  scientific  thinkers,  attached  great 
value  to  a  popular  exposition  of  the  principles  of  his  dis- 
coveries. Descartes  required  a  Fontenelle  and  Newton  a 
Voltaire  to  make  their  ideas  accessible  and  useful  to  the 
mass  of  students.  Laplace  was  his  own  Fontenelle  and 
Voltaire.  "  Few  works,"  says  Sir  John  Herschel,  "  have 
been  more  extensively  read,  or  more  generally  appreciated, 
than  Laplace's  '  Essai  philosophique  sur  les  Probabilites,' 
and  that  on  the  '  Systeme  du  Monde '  by  the  same  author. 
It  is  not,  perhaps,  too  much  to  say  that  were  all  the 
literature  of  Europe  to  perish,  these  two  essays  excepted, 
they  would  suffice  to  convey  to  the  latest  posterity  an 
impression  of  the  intellectual  greatness  of  the  age  which 
could  produce  them,  surpassing  that  afforded  by  all  the 
monuments  antiquity  has  left  us.  Previous  to  the  pub- 
lication of  the  '  Essai  philosophique,'  few,  except  professed 
mathematicians  or  persons  conversant  with  assurances 
and  similar  commercial  risks,  possessed  any  knowledge  of 
the  principles  of  this  calculus,  or  troubled  themselves 
about  its  conclusions,  regarding  them  as  merely  curious 
and  perhaps  not  altogether  harmless  speculations.  Thence- 
forward, however,  apathy  was  speedily  exchanged  for  a 
lively  and  increasing  desire  to  know  something  of  a  system 
of  reasoning  which  for  the  first  time  seemed  to  afford  a 
handle  for  some  kind  of  exact  inquiry  into  matters  no  one 
had  ever  expected  to  see  reduced  to  calculation,  and  bear- 


124  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

ing  on  the  most  important  concerns  of  life.  Men  began 
to  hear  with  surprise,  not  unmingled  with  some  vague 
hope  of  ultimate  benefit,  that  not  only  births,  deaths,  and 
marriages,  but  the  decisions  of  tribunals,  the  results  of 
popular  elections,  the  influence  of  punishments  in  check- 
ing crime,  the  comparative  value  of  medical  remedies  and 
different  modes  of  treatment  of  diseases,  the  probable 
limits  of  error  in  numerical  results  in  every  department 
of  physical  inquiry,  the  detection  of  causes,  physical, 
social,  and  moral — nay,  even  the  weight  of  evidence  and 
the  validity  of  logical  argument — might  come  to  be  sur- 
veyed with  that  lynx-eyed  scrutiny  of  a  dispassionate 
analysis,  which,  if  not  at  once  leading  to  the  discovery  of 
positive  truth,  would  at  least  secure  the  detection  and 
proscription  of  many  mischievous  and  besetting  fallacies." 
Both  ways  of  approaching  the  intricate  phenomena  of 
nature  and  history,  that  of  mechanics  dealing  with  the 
general  laws  of  motion  and  of  lifeless  masses,  and  that 
of  statistics  dealing  with  the  arithmetical  properties  of 
large  numbers  of  units,  leave  out  of  consideration  that 
hidden  and  mysterious  phenomenon  to  which  alone  is 
attached,  if  not  order  and  method,  yet  certainly  all 
that  commands  interest  in  the  created  world :  the  factor 
se.  of  life — the  existence  of  individuality.  The  view  which 

Laplace 

gained  his     Laplace  took  of  the  universe  or  of  human  affairs  is  an 

results  by 

f'^^;.    attempt  to  see  how  far  science  and   reasoning   can   go 

ni£j  tile  prin-  •*•  wo 

dlviduaVity.  while  disregarding  the  principle  of  individuality.1     The 


1  See  Clerk  Maxwell  on  '  Science 
and  Freewill'  (Life  by  Campbell 
and  Garnett,  p.  438) :  "  Two  kinds 
of  knowledge,  which  we  may  call  for 
convenience  dynamical  and  statis- 
tical. The  statistical  method  of 


investigating  social  questions  has 
Laplace  for  its  most  scientific  and 
Buckle  for  its  most  popular  ex- 
pounder. Persons  are  grouped 
according  to  some  characteristic, 
and  the  number  of  persons  forming 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


125 


method  has  been  most  fruitful,  and,  far  from  being  ex- 
hausted, promises  undreamt  of  results  in  the  future.  It 
was  probably  more  from  the  desire  to  keep  his  view 
clear  and  his  method  simple,  than  with  any  necessarily 
sceptical  tendency,  that  when  Laplace  was  questioned  by 
Napoleon  how  it  was  that  in  the  great  volumes  of  the 
'  Mecanique  celeste '  the  name  of  God  did  not  appear,  he 
replied,  "  Sire,  je  n'ai  pas  besoin  de  cette  hypothese." 

But  French  science  did  not  leave  that  great  field  of 
research  uncultivated,  which  is  the  very  playground  of 

J     r     J& 

individual  life.  Its  cultivation  was  the  work  of  that 
other  great  representative  of  French  science — the  con- 
temporary  of  Laplace — Georges  Cuvier.1  Linnaeus  had 


27. 

Individu- 
ality the 
centre  of 


the  group  is  set  down  under  that 
characteristic.  This  is  the  raw 
material  from  which  the  statist 
endeavours  to  deduce  general  theo- 
rems in  sociology.  Other  students 
of  human  nature  proceed  on  a  dif- 
ferent plan.  They  observe  indi- 
vidual men,  ascertain  their  history, 
analyse  their  motives,  and  compare 
their  expectation  of  what  they  will 
do  with  their  actual  conduct.  This 
may  be  called  the  dynamical  method 
of  study  as  applied  to  man.  How- 
ever imperfect  the  dynamical  study 
of  man  may  be  in  practice,  it  evi- 
dently is  the  only  perfect  method 
in  principle,  and  its  shortcomings 
arise  from  the  limitation  of  our 
powers  rather  than  from  a  faulty 
method  of  procedure.  If  we  be- 
take ourselves  to  the  statistical 
method,  we  do  so  confessing  that 
we  are  unable  to  follow  the  details 
of  each  individual  case,  and  expect- 
ing that  the  effects  of  widespread 
causes,  though  very  different  in  each 
individual,  will  produce  an  average 
result  on  the  whole  nation,  from  a 
study  of  which  we  may  estimate 
the  character  and  propensities  of 


the  sciences 
of  life. 


an  imaginary  being  called  the  Mean 
Man." 

1  It  is  not  necessary  here  to  ex- 
plain the  reasons  which  have  in- 
duced me  to  confine  myself  mainly 
to  the  two  great  names  of  Laplace 
and  Cuvier  as  the  great  repre- 
sentatives of  the  exact  scientific 
spirit,  as  it  first  asserted  its  su- 
premacy in  France,  and  from  there 
gradually  fought  its  way  all  over 
Europe.  To  me  it  seems  that  no- 
where has  this  modern  scientific 
spirit  been  represented  in  greater 
completeness  and  greater  purity. 
This  is  so  much  the  more  remark- 
able, as  other  influences  and  tempta- 
tions were  not  wanting  in  that  age 
and  country  which  might  have  in- 
terfered with  the  application  of 
the  purely  scientific  method.  The 
scientific  spirit  is  in  danger  of  being 
contaminated  by  two  interests  which 
are  essentially  foreign  to  it :  the 
one  is  the  practical,  the  other  the 
philosophical.  Frequently  they  are 
united ;  and  when  united  their  influ- 
ence on  the  progress  of  science  has 
frequently  been  disastrous.  In  no 
department  of  knowledge  has  this 


126 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


begun  the  work  of  natural  history  by  inventing  a  system 
of  classification  and  a  technical  language  or  nomenclature. 
Buffon  in  his  brilliant  and  elegant  portraits  had  cast  around 
it  the  charms  of  poetry  and  romance.  Jussieu  had  im- 
ported botany  from  Sweden  into  France,  and  in  the  garden 
of  Trianon  had  given  a  living  model  of  the  arrangement 
of  plants;  botanising  had  become  popular  through  the 

psychological  as  a  physical  side, 
and  a  philanthropic  as  much  as 
a  scientific  interest.  In  respect  of 
this  it  is  well  to  note  that  the  age 
and  country  which  gave  to  Europe 
the  great  models  of  purely  scientific 
research  in  Laplace  and  Cuvier  was 
rich  also  in  great  thinkers  who 
applied  themselves  in  a  philoso- 
phical spirit  to  the  advancement  of 
scientific  and  practical  medicine,  to 
the  reform  of  hospitals,  to  the  care 
of  the  insane,  to  the  education  of 
the  deaf  and  dumb.  The  whole 
school  of  the  ideologues,  headed  by 
Condorcet,  Cabanis,  and  Destutt 
de  Tracy,  was  closely  allied  with 
the  medical  profession.  But  how- 
ever important  this  side  of  French 
thought  may  have  been,  its  in- 
fluence on  the  rest  of  Europe  at 
that  time  cannot  be  compared 
with  that  of  the  purely  scientific 
writings  belonging  to  mathematics 
and  natural  science.  Such  names 
as  Cabanis  and  Bichat  belong  to 
a  different  current  of  European 
thought,  which  I  purposely  separate 
from  the  exact  or  purely  scientific. 
And  this  separation  is  justified  his- 
torically by  the  fact  that  in  the 
Academic  des  Sciences  for  a  con- 
siderable time  medical  science  was 
only  meagrely  represented,  whilst 
philosophy  during  the  period  of  the 
suppression  of  the  Academic  des 
Sciences  morales  et  politiques,  from 
1803-1832,  had  no  academic  re- 
presentation at  all.  The  great 
name  of  Bichat  is  not  among  the 
Academicians,  and  Cuvier  himself 


union  of  the  practical  and  philo- 
sophical spirit  been  more  marked 
than  in  the  medical  sciences.  Essen- 
tially interested  as  it  is  in  the  im- 
mediate application  of  scientific  dis- 
coveries to  the  needs  of  suffering 
mankind,  we  witness  in  the  course 
of  the  seventeenth  and  eighteenth 
centuries  a  one-sided  alliance  of  the 
art  of  healing  with  chemistry  (Sylvi- 
us, 1614-1672),  with  physics  (Borelli, 
1608-1679),  and  with  mechanics  (Pit- 
cairn,  1652-1713),  and  the  reaction 
of  the  animists  (Stahl,  1660-1734, 
and  Hoffmann,  1660-1742),  and  the 
vitalists  (Bordeu,  1722-1776,  and 
Barthez,  1734-1806).  A  large  por- 
tion of  the  history  of  medicine  (see 
Haeser,  '  Geschichte  der  Medicin,' 
Jena,  1881,  voL  ii.,  and  Guardia, 
'  Histoire  de  la  Medecine,'  Paris, 
1884)  consists  in  the  account  of  the 
opposition  to  premature  generalisa- 
tions, adopted  from  other  sciences, 
or  still  more  dangerously  from  meta- 
physics. As  examples  of  the  meta- 
physical tendency  we  have  the  Scotch 
systems  of  Cullen  and  Brown,  and 
the  German  "Philosophy  of  Nature." 
The  reasons  why  philosophy  has  so 
frequently  allied  itself  with  medi- 
cine, thus  preventing  the  purely 
scientific  spirit  from  gaining  ad- 
mission, are  twofold.  "  Young 
men,"  says  Cuvier,  "adopt  these 
theories  with  enthusiasm,  because 
they  seem  to  abridge  their  studies 
and  to  give  a  thread  in  an  almost 
inextricable  labyrinth  "  ('  Rapport.' 
p.  333).  The  other  reason  is  that 
the  art  of  healing  has  as  much  a 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


127 


writings  of  Eousseau ;  gardening  and  the  study  of  plant- 
life  had  become  a  royal  pastime,  and  a  favourite  recrea- 
tion for  those  oppressed  with  the  troubles  of  the  State 
or  the  sorrows  of  private  life.  Cuvier,  while  asking  the 
reason  why  other  portions  of  natural  history  had  not 
shared  the  same  attention,  breaks  out  into  the  following 
eloquent  words :  "  The  study  of  animals  presents  dim- 


explains  the  exclusive  attitude  of 
the  Academy  to  the  medical  pro- 
fession in  his  Eloges  of  Halle,  Cor- 
visart,  and  Pinel  ('Eloges,' vol.  iii.  p. 
339,  &c. )  See  also  Maury  (p.  304) : 
"  Les  sciences  physiques,  chimiques 
et  naturelles  avaient  pris  une  telle 
extension  dans  les  travaux  de 
1'Academie,  qu'a  la  fin  du  dix- 
huitieme  siecle,  la  medecine,  qui 
n'y  avait  jamais  e"te  au  reste  bien 
largement  representee,  fut  de  plus 
en  plus  releguee  a  1'arriere  plan  ; 
ce  n'etait  plus  que  de  loin  en  loin 
que  les  medecins,  les  chirurgiens  de 
la  Compagnie,  .  .  .  y  presentaient 
des  observations  sur  des  points 
medicaux.  ...  La  medecine,  qui, 
selon  la  juste  observation  de  Cabanis, 
tend  aux  hypotheses  par  la  nature 
meme  du  sujet  auquelelles'applique, 
n'offrait  point  assez  de  Constance 
dans  ses  principes  et  d'evidence 
dans  ses  demonstrations  pour  satis- 
faire  des  esprits  qui  se  de"tachaient 
tous  les  jours  davantage  des  vieilles 
speculations  de  1'ecole.  C'est  ce  qui 
explique  le  peu  de  favour  qu'elle 
rencontrait  a  1' Academic."  To  what 
extent  this  rigid  demarcation,  ac- 
cording to  which  "  observations 
relatives  aux  dispositions  morales 
et  intellectuelles  des  individus 
n'entrent  assurement  dans  les 
attributions  d'aucune  academic  des 
sciences  "  ('  Memoires  de  1'Institut,' 
vol.  ix.  p.  110),  was  beneficial  to 
medical  science  is  an  important 
question.  In  the  organisation  of 
the  Institute  of  the  3rd  brumaire,  an 
iv.  (25th  October  1795),  there  are 


awarded  out  of  60  members  only  6 
to  medicine  and  surgery  combined, 
and  in  the  "  nouvelle  organisation  " 
of  3rd  pluviose,  an  xi.  (23rd  January 
1803),  there  are  6  members  out  of 
63.  This  section  is  given  as  the  last, 
even  after  "  economic  rurale  et  art 
veterinaire"  (see  Aucoc,  'L'Institut,' 
p.  3,  &c.)  It  is  interesting  to  note 
how  in  contrast  to  this  the  medical 
profession  occupied  for  a  long  period 
a  foremost  place  in  the  Royal  Society 
of  London,  so  much  so  that  fre- 
quently opposition  was  made  to  the 
admission  of  new  members  belong- 
ing to  it  (see  Weld,  '  History  of  the 
Royal  Society,'  vol.  i.  chap.  4  ;  vol. 
ii.  p.  153).  Of  5336  papers  contained 
in  the  '  Philosophical  Transactions  ' 
from  1665  to  1848,  1020,  the  largest 
number  in  any  department,  belonged 
to  anatomy,  physiology,  and  medi- 
cine (ibid.,  vol.  ii.  p.  565).  Babbage 
complained  of  the  influence  of  the 
Colleges  of  Physicians  and  Surgeons 
in  the  Royal  Society,  as  occasionally 
filling  the  pages  of  the  'Transac- 
tions '  with  medical  papers  of  very 
moderate  merit ;  and  also  because 
the  preponderance  of  the  medical 
interest  introduces  into  the  Society 
some  of  the  jealousies  of  that  pro- 
fession ('Decline  of  Science  in  Eng- 
land,' 1830,  p.  188).  In  the  founda- 
tion of  the  British  Association  this 
union  with  the  medical  interest 
was  dropped ;  though  the  older 
"Versammlung  deutscher  Natur- 
forscher  und  Arzte,"  after  which 
it  was  modelled,  established  and 
maintained  that  union. 


128 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


28. 

Into  this 
centre 
Cuvier  car- 
ried exact 
research. 


culties  which  only  great  zeal  can  surmount ;  we  have 
to  subject  them  to  torments  in  order  to  appreciate  their 
physical  powers ;  their  innermost  energies  only  reveal 
themselves  to  the  dissecting-knife — only  by  living  among 
corpses  can  we  discover  them.  Among  them  we  find  the 
same  spectacle  as  in  the  world,  whatever  moralists  may 
say :  they  are  hardly  less  wicked  or  less  unhappy  than 
we  are;  the  arrogance  of  the  strong,  the  meanness  of 
the  weak,  vile  rapacity,  short  pleasures  bought  by  great 
efforts — death  brought  on  by  long  suffering — that  is  the 
rule  among  animals  as  much  as  among  men.  With 
plants  existence  is  not  surrounded  by  pain — no  sad 
image  tarnishes  their  splendour  before  our  eyes,  nothing 
reminds  us  of  our  passions,  our  cares,  our  misfortunes — 
love  is  there  without  jealousy,  beauty  without  vanity, 
force  without  tyranny,  death  without  anguish — nothing 
resembles  human  nature." l 

Into  the  centre  of  individual  and  organised  life — the 
life  of  the  animal  and  human  creation — Cuvier  carried 
exact  research,  grounding  it  on  the  science  of  compara- 
tive anatomy.2  At  the  same  time,  he  marked  out  as  the 
principal  problem,  around  which  all  investigations  must 
turn,  and  upon  which  all  classification  must  depend, 


1  'Elogeshistoriques,'vol.  i.  p.  91. 

2  Cuvier,  in  the  Introduction  to 
'  Le  Regne  animal,  distribue  d'apres 
son  organisation,  pour  servir  de  base 
a  1'histoire  naturelle  des  animaux 
et  d 'introduction  a  1'anatomie  com- 
pareV  (Paris,  1817),  says  that  for 
thirty  years  he  had  devoted  to  com- 
parative anatomy  all  his  time  (p. 
v),  that  the  first   results  had  ap- 
peared in  1795,  his  '  Lecons  d' Ana- 
tomic comparee'  in   1800  (p.  vii), 
that  he  has  made  anatomy  and  zool- 


ogy march  side  by  side  (p.  vi).  He 
compares  natural  history  as  a  science 
with  other  sciences,  stating  that 
dynamics  is  become  a  science  almost 
entirely  of  calculation,  that  chem- 
istry is  still  a  science  altogether  of 
experiments,  that  natural  history 
will  for  a  long  time  to  come  remain 
in  most  of  its  parts  a  science  of  ob- 
servation (p.  5) ;  he  maintains  that 
geometry  is  a  study  of  syllogisms, 
natural  history  a  study  of  method 
(p.  xviii). 


THE    SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


129 


the  phenomenon  of  individual  life,  that  great  vortex  into 
which  agencies,  processes,  and  the  elements  of  inorganic 
nature  are  continually  drawn,  from  which  they  are  con- 
tinually ejected,  preserving  not  the  unity  of  substance 
but,  among  changing  events,  the  unity  of  form.1 

"  It  is  not,"  he  says,  "  in  the  substance  that  in  plants 
and  animals  the  identity  of  the  species  is  manifested,  it  is 
in  the  form.  There  are  probably  not  two  men,  two  oaks, 
two  rose-trees,  which  have  the  compound  elements  of 
their  bodies  in  the  same  proportion — and  even  these 
elements  change  without  end,  they  circulate  rather  than 
reside  in  that  abstract  and  figured  space  which  we  call 
the  form ;  in  a  few  years  probably  there  is  not  left  one 
atom  of  that  which  constitutes  our  body  to-day — only  the 
form  is  persistent ;  the  form  alone  perpetuates  in  multiply- 
ing itself ;  transmitted  by  the  mysterious  operation  which 
we  call  generation  to  an  endless  series  of  individuals,  it 
will  attract  successively  to  itself  numberless  molecules  of 
different  matter,  all  of  them  merely  transient." 2 


1  "  La  vie  est  done  un  tourbillon 
plus  ou  moins  rapide,  plus  ou  moins 
complique,  dont  la  direction  est 
constante,  et  qui  entraine  toujours 
des  molecules  de  memes  sortes, 
mais  ou  les  molecules  individuelles 
entrent  et  d'ou  elles  sortent  con- 
tinuellement,  de  maniere  que  la 
forme  du  corps  vivant  lui  est  plus 
essentielle  que  la  matiere"  ('Regne 
animal,'  p.  13,  &c.)  "  II  vient 
sans  cesse  des  elements  du  dehors 
en  dedans  :  il  s'en  e"chappe  du  de- 
dans au  dehors :  toutes  les  parties 
sont  dans  un  tourbillon  continuel, 
qui  est  une  condition  essentielle  du 
phenomena,  et  que  nous  ne  pouvons 
suspendre  longtemps  sans  1'arreter 
pour  jamais.  Les  branches  les  plus 
simples  de  1'histoire  naturelle  par- 

VOL.  I. 


ticipent  de"ja  a  cette  complication 
et  a  ce  mouvement  perpe'tuel,  qui 
rendent  si  difficile  1'application  des 
sciences  ge'ne'rales  "( 'Rapport, '  p.  1 50, 
&c. )  "  Dans  les  corps  vivans  chaque 
partie  a  sa  composition  propre  et 
distincte ;  aucune  de  leurs  mole- 
cules ne  reste  en  place ;  toutes 
entrent  et  sortent  successivement : 
la  vie  est  un  tourbillon  continuel, 
dont  la  direction,  toute  compliquee 
qu'elle  est,  demeure  constante,  ainsi 
que  1'espece  des  molecules  qui  y 
sont  entrainees,  mais  non  les  mole"- 
cules  individuelles  elles-memes.  .  .  . 
Ainsi  la  forme  de  ces  corps  leur  est 
plus  essentielle  que  leur  matiere," 
&c.  (ibid.,  p.  200). 

2  '  l£loges  historiques,'  vol.  iii.  p. 
156. 


130 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


Keeping  this  unity  of  form,  this  absorbing  vortex  of 
life,  the  totality  of  organisation,  always  before  him, 
Cuvier,  in  surveying  the  whole  region  of  animated 
nature,1  fixes  finally  for  tha  purposes  of  classification  and 
division  on  that  system  of  organs  which  expresses  most 
truly  the  peculiarity  of  each  of  the  great  branches  into 
which  he  divides  the  animal  world — namely,  the  nervous 
system.2  But  rather  than  follow  him  at  present  into  the 

1  "  La  partie  anatomique  du  prob- 
leine  general  de  la  vie  est  resolue 
depuis  longtemps  pour  les  animaux. 
au  moins  pour  ceux  d'entre  eux  qui 
nous  interessent  le  plus.     Les  voies 
que  les   substances  y   parcourent, 
sont  connues ;    .    .     .    il   apei^oit 
aussi  comment  ces  routes,  si  com- 
pliquees  dans  1'homme,  se  simpli- 
fieut  par  degres  dans  les  animaux 
inferieurs,  et  finissent  par  se  reduire 
a   une  spongiosite  uniforme.      Les 
recherches  de  M.  Cuvier — dans  les 
lemons    d'anatomie    compare* — ont 
acheve"  d'assigner  a  chaque  animal 
sa  place  dans  la  grande  e"chelle  dea 
complications  de  structure"  ('Rap- 
port,' p.  202,  &c.) 

2  It  is  not  my  object  here  to  give 
an  account  of  the  views  of  Cuvier, 
still  less  of   his   contributions    to 
natural  history,  which — in  spite  of 
the  special  theories  and  laws  which 
he  and  his  followers  established  (see 
especially  Flourens,    'Histoire  des 
Travaux   de   Georges   Cuvier,'  3me 
&L,  1858) — remained  in  his  hands 
to  the  last  pre-eminently  a  science 
of  observation.     It  has  been  pointed 
out  that  Cuvier  only  gradually  (pro- 
bably about  1812)  arrived  at  the  final 
principle  of  division — viz.,  the  ner- 
vous system— and  that  he  adopted 
it  from  others  (notably  Yirey  and 
De  Blainville),  that  before  18*12  he 
had  successively  used  the  organs  of 
generation  (1795),  of  nutrition,  and 
of  circulation  as  principles  of  clas- 
sification.    In  his  Report  of  1808, 


in  mentioning  his  own  labours,  he 
says:  "  M.  Cuvier,  en  etudiant  la 
physiologic  des  animaux  vertebras, 
a  trouve  dans  la  quantite  respective 
de  leur  respiration,  la  raison  de  leur 
quantite  de  mouvemeus,  et  par  con- 
sequent de  I'espece  de  ces  mouve- 
mens.  ...  En  effet,  M.  Cuvier, 
ayant  examine  les  modifications  qu' 
eprouvent  dans  les  animaux  sans 
vertebrea  les  organes  de  la  circula- 
tion, de  la  respiration,  et  des  sensa- 
tions, et  ayant  calcule  les  resultats 
necessaires  de  ces  modifications,  en 
a  deduit  une  division  nouvelle  ou 
ces  animaux  sont  ranges  suivant 
leurs  veritables  rapports"  ('Rap- 
port,' p.  311,  &c. )  Compare  also 
Carus,  '  Geschichte  der  Zoologie, ' 
Miinchen,  1872,  p.  602  ;  Flourens, 
"  Eloge  de  Cuvier,"  in  his  'Eloges 
bistoriques,'  3me  serie,  Paris,  1862, 
p.  122,  &c.  ;  Halm  in  the  :  Graude 
Encyclopedic,'  article  "Cuvier. "  See 
also  the  Introduction  to  the  '  Regne 
animal,'  which  proposes  to  arrange 
living  beings  according  to  their  "  or- 
ganisation,'' by  investigating  their 
"  structure,"  their  "internal  as  well 
as  external  conformation."  Cuvier 
here  states  that  no  one  before  had 
tried  to  arrange  the  classes  and 
orders  according  to  the  "  ensemble 
de  la  structure  "  (p.  vi).  He  is  thus 
led  to  the  law  of  the  "  subordination 
des  caracteres,  .  .  .  ayaut  soin 
d'etablir  toujours  la  correspond- 
ance  des  formes  exterieures  et  in- 
terieures  qui,  les  unes  comme  les 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


131 


details  of  his  natural  history,  his  comparative  anatomy, 
or  his  palaeontology,  of  which  latter  sciences  he  is  the 
creator,  it  serves  our  present  purpose  better  to  learn  how 
he  viewed  the  object  of  natural  science  in  general — how 
he  defined  its  task.  As  the  first  step  in  civilisation  was 
the  creation  of  a  language  possessing  definite  rules,  so 
the  first  step  in  the  growth  of  a  science  is  that  taken  by 
Linnaeus,  who  was  not  terrified  by  this  enormous  work, 
that  of  giving  names,  of  framing  a  nomenclature.1  "  But," 
says  Cuvier,  "  to  name  well,  you  must  know  well.  These 


autres,  font  partie  integrants  de 
1'essence  de  chaque  animal "  (p.  xiv). 
He  opposes  former  artificial  classifi- 
cations, such  as  the  principle  that 
living  beings  can  be  arranged  "  de 
maniere  a  former  des  etres  une 
seule  ligne"  (p.  xx).  "Un  etre 
organise"  est  un  tout  unique,  un 
ensemble  de  parties  qui  reagissent 
les  unes  sur  les  autres  pour  produire 
un  effet  cornmun.  Nulle  de  ses 
parties  ne  peut  done  etre  modifide 
essentiellement  sans  que  toutes  les 
autres  ne  s'en  ressentent "  ('  Eloges,' 
vol.  ii.  p.  279). 

1  The  formation  of  a  nomencla- 
ture or  a  terminology  is  one  of  the 
most  important  steps  in  the  begin- 
ning and  the  progress  of  science. 
Cuvier  refers  frequently  to  this: 
"  Nos  livres  saints,  a  leur  debut, 
nous  representent  le  Createur  fais- 
ant  passer  ses  ouvrages  sous  les 
yeux  du  premier  homme,  et  lui 
ordonnant  de  leur  imposer  des 
noms.  .  .  .  Ces  uoms,  qu'il  est 
present  a  1'homme  d'imposer,  ne 
sont  pas  des  signes  incoherens  ap- 
pliques au  hasard  a  quelques  objets 
isolds.  Pour  qu'ils  deviennent  re- 
guliers  et  significatifs,  ils  exigent, 
comme  il  est  dit,  que  les  etres  aient 
passe  devant  le  nomenclateur " 
('  Kloges,'  vol.  iii.  pp.  450,  452).  No- 
where is  terminology  more  import- 


ant than  in  chemistry.  "  L'un  des 
moyens  qui  ont  le  plus  puissamment 
contribud  a  faciliter  l'enseignement 
de  la  science  en  gdndral,  et  a  pre- 
parer  1'adoption  universelle  de  la 
theorie  nouvelle,  c'est  la  nomen- 
clature crede  par  cette  societd  de 
chimistes  fran9ais.  .  .  .  Donneraux 
eldmens  des  noms  simples ;  en 
deriver,  pour  les  combinaisous,  des 
noms,  qui  exprimassent  1'espece  et 
la  proportion  des  dlemens  qui  les 
constituent,  c'etait  offrir  d'avance 
a  1'esprit  le  tableau  abregd  des  re- 
sultats  de  la  science,  c'dtait  fournir 
a  la  memoire  le  moyen  de  rappeler 
par  les  noms  la  nature  meme  des 
objets.  C'est  ce  que  M.  Guyton 
de  Morveau  proposa  le  premier  des 
1781,  et  ce  qui  fut  completement 
execute  par  lui  et  par  ses  collegues 
en  1787"  ('Rapport,'  p.  88,  &c.)  Cf. 
'  Eloges,'  vol.  iii.  pp.  194,  482,  496. 
Cuvier  ('Eloges,'  vol.  iii.  p.  302) 
mentions  ' '  cette  antipathic  pour 
les  methodes  et  pour  une  nomencla- 
ture precise  a  laquelle  Buffon  s'est 
laissd  aller  en  tant  d'endroits"  ;  he 
speaks  of  Pinel  "  qui  avait  cherche 
d'abord  a  former  pour  les  descrip- 
tions des  maladies  un  langage  prd- 
cis,  modele  sur  celui  que  Linnseus 
avait  introduit  en  botanique"  (ibid., 
vol.  iii.  p.  386). 


132  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

beings  and  their  parts  which  are  to  be  known  are  to  be 
counted  by  the  million ;  it  is  not  enough  to  know  them 
singly,  for  they  are  submitted  to  an  order,  to  mutual 
relations,  which  must  likewise  be  appreciated,  for  it  is 
according  to  this  order  that  each  has  its  part  to  play, 
that  each  disappears  at  its  time,  that  they  reappear  simi- 
larly made,  always  in  the  same  proportions,  and  armed 
with  the  necessary  forces  and  faculties  for  the  main- 
tenance of  these  proportions,  and  of  the  whole  of  this 
perpetual  vortex.  Not  only  is  each  being  an  organism, 
the  whole  universe  is  one,  but  many  million  times  more 
complicated ;  and  that  which  the  anatomist  does  for 
a  single  animal — for  the  microcosm — the  naturalist  is 
to  do  for  the  macrocosm,  for  the  universal  animal, 
for  the  play  of  this  alarming  aggregation  of  partial 
organisms." l 

It  was  this  sustained  regard  for  the  value  of  detailed 
research  and  minute  observation,  coupled  with  an  equal 
appreciation  of  the  unity  of  all  regions  of  existence, 
and  all  branches  of  learning,  that  elevated  Cuvier  to 
the  height  of  the  science  of  his  age  and  his  country, 
and  made  him  a  true  exponent  of  the  modern  scientific 
spirit.  The  works  of  Newton  and  Laplace  may  contain 
more  formulae  of  lasting  value,  more  instruments  of  per- 
manent scientific  use — they  may,  for  all  time,  have  traced 
a  few  lines  of  the  enwoven  cipher  of  the  all-pervading 
mechanism  of  nature  ;  it  is,  however,  well  to  note  that  he 
only  who  keeps  in  steadfast  view  the  life  rather  than  the 
mechanism  of  existence,  approaches  the  great  secret  of 
nature,  and  gauges  rightly  the  value  of  each  component 

1  Cuvier,  'Eloges  historiques, '  vol.  iii.  p.  453. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


133 


part,  or  the  worth  of  each  human  effort.1  In  this  respect 
the  nineteenth  century  knows  no  greater  figure  than 
Cuvier;  not  even  Humboldt,  great  and  comprehensive  as 
was  his  scientific  view.  The  advantages  also  of  Cuvier's 
position  as  permanent  Secretary  of  the  French  Academy 
of  Sciences  were  exceptional,  and  well  fitted  to  bring  out 
his  extraordinary  talents.  We  can  say  that  in  him  science 
has  become  fully  conscious  of  its  true  methods,  its  useful- 
ness, its  most  becoming  style,  its  inherent  dignity,  its  past 
errors,  its  present  triumphs,  the  endless  career  which  lies 
before  it,  and  the  limits  which  it  cannot  transgress. 

Educated  in  Germany,  at  the  same  school  as  Schiller 
and    Dannecker,2   imbued   by   early   experience   and   by  trailing. 


29. 
Cuvier's 


1  "  C'est  la  continuation  cle  ce  com- 
mandement  de  voir  et  de  uommer, 
par  oft  s'ouvre  la  vie  de  notre  espece, 
c'est  la  voie  qui  devait  nous  con- 
duire  soit  a  des  contemplations  plus 
hautes,  soit  seulement  a  des  inven- 
tions   utiles.      En    effet    1'histoire 
naturelle   ne  fait  aucun   pas   sans 
que  la  physiologic  et  la  philosophic 
generate  marchent   d'un   pas  e'gal, 
et  sans  que  la  society  receive  leur 
tribut  commun  "  ('Eloges,'  vol.  iii. 
p.  474). 

2  Cuvier  has  himself  written  an 
account  of  his  early  life  and  studies. 
It  is  given  by  Flourens,  '  Eloges,'  vol. 
i.  pp.  167-193.   He  was  born  in  1769, 
of    a    Protestant  stock,    at  Mont- 
beliard,  the  capital  of  a  small  prin- 
cipality, situated  in  the  Jura,  and 
then    belonging    to    Wiirtemberg. 
The  autocratic  Duke  Charles  (1737- 
1793)  had  founded  a  military  acad- 
emy in  Stuttgart,  his  capital,  where 
400    youths   were  at   his    expense 
housed  and  educated  according  to 
a  strict  rule,  but  under  the  guid- 
ance of  enlightened  masters,  and  in 
a  thoroughly  modern  spirit.     The 
institution   was   a   kind    of    oppo- 


sition to  the  Protestant  Church 
rule,  which  had  very  early  spread 
a  system  of  popular  and  compulsory 
education  throughout  the  country. 
It  is  a  chapter  of  history  well  worth 
reading.  The  great  problems  of 
popular  education  as  against  higher 
instruction,  Protestant  discipline  in 
the  lower  as  against  military  dis- 
cipline in  the  higher  schools,  the 
democratic  as  against  the  aristo- 
cratic spirit,  the  independence  as 
against  the  State  -  regulation  of 
University  teaching,  were  fought 
out  by  the  dukes  and  the  Estates 
of  Wiirtemberg  in  a  prolonged  war- 
fare, a  sample  of  similar  movements 
all  over  Germany,  and  well  told  by 
Perthes  in  his  '  Politische  Zustiinde 
und  Personen  in  Deutschland  zur 
Zeit  der  franzosischen  Herrschaft" 
(Gotha,  1862,  pp.  501-548).  Cuvier 
evidently  saw  the  better  side  of  the 
system,  for  he  entered  after  the 
imperious  character  of  the  duke 
had  been  subdued  by  the  victorious 
estates.  Forced  to  change  his  ways, 
which  he  conscientiously  did,  the 
duke  laid  by  for  his  country,  as  a 
local  historian  says,  "  a  fund  of  in- 


134 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


personal  contact  with  that  spirit  of  general  education 
and  universal  training  which  then  animated  the  German- 
speaking  nations  of  the  Continent,  thoroughly  grounded 
in  classics  and  mathematics,  with .  a  cosmopolitan  know- 
ledge of  languages  and  literature,  which  fitted  him  to 
understand  the  merits  of  different  nations,  he  became 
the  great  exponent  of  that  peculiar  system  of  higher 
culture  which  since  the  time  of  Colbert  the  French  had 
elaborated — the  academic  system.1  The  centre  of  this 


telligence  and  acquisitions  by  which 
we  have  benefited  up  to  modern 
times"  (Perthes,  p.  510).  We  know 
the  other  and  older  side  of  the 
picture  from  the  '  Life  of  Schiller ' 
(see,  inter  alia,  Carlyle,  '  Life  of 
Schiller,'  collected  works,  library 
edition,  vol.  v.  p.  258).  Cuvier 
gives  a  long  description  of  the  "  Karl- 
schule  "  :  "  C'etait  un  etablisse- 
ment  vraiment  magnifique.  Envi- 
ron quatre  cents  boursiers  et  pen- 
sionnaires,  loges  dans  un  edifice  tel 
qu'il  n'y  en  a  aucun  d'approchant 
en  Europe  (parmi  ceux  qui  sont 
consacres  a  1'instruction  de  la  jeun- 
esse),  vetus  d'un  bel  uniforme,  con- 
duits par  des  officiers  et  des  sous- 
officiers  tires  des  regiments  du  due, 
reeevaient  des  lecons  de  tout  genre 
de  plus  de  quatre-vingts  maitres  ou 
professeurs.  On  a  beaucoup  parle 
de  1'esprit  de  despotisme  avec  lequel 
le  due  disposait  de  leurs  personnes 
et  choisissait  pour  chacun  d'eux 
1'etat  qu'il  devait  embrasser,  et  je 
crois  en  effet  qu'il  en  etait  ainsi 
dans  l'origine  de  1'etablissement  ; 
mais  de  mon  temps,  je  n'ai  rien 
vu  de  semblable,  et  ce  qui  est  cer- 
tain, c'est  que  personne  ne  pretendit 
rneme  me  donner  de  conseil  h.  cet 
egard.  II  y  avait  cinq  facultes 
superieures,  droit,  medecine,  admin- 
istration, militaire  et  commerce" 
(Flourens,  loc.  cit.,  p.  171). 

1  The  first  great   representative 


of  this  academic  spirit  and  culture 
was  Fontenelle,  who,  living  during 
a  hundred  years,  from  1657  to  1757, 
was  Secretary  of  the  Academic  des 
Sciences  during  forty  -  two  years, 
from  1699  (the  year  of  the  recon- 
stitution  of  the  Academy)  to  1741. 
Among  his  successors  were  men  like 
Condorcet,  Delambre,  Cuvier,  and 
Arago.  Fontenelle  gave  to  scien- 
tific subjects  a  dignified  popularity, 
separated  the  departments  of  science 
and  metaphysics,  kept  the  scientific 
interest  free  from  the  commercial, 
and  through  his  connection  with  the 
Academic  franchise  did  probably 
more  than  any  other  writer  to  es- 
tablish that  superiority  of  style  and 
diction  for  which  the  great  French 
men  of  science  are  so  remarkable  and 
so  superior  to  those  of  other  coun- 
tries. Bertrand,  him  self  a  successor 
of  Fontenelle,  says  of  him :  "  Pretant 
aux  travaux  de  ses  confreres  la 
finesse  de  ses  apercus  et  la  vivacite 
ingenieuse  de  son  style,  il  a  su  dans 
leurs  portraits,  qui  sont  des  chefs- 
d'oouvre,  plus  encore  que  dans  1'ana- 
lyse  de  leurs  de'couvertes,  donner 
aux  plus  humbles  et  aux  plus 
modestes  une  celebrite  imprevue 
et  durable,  et  le  juste  et  serieux 
hommage  qu'il  rend  au  vrai  merite 
fait  aimer  et  respecter  tout  h  la  fois 
les  savants  et  la  science"  ('L'Aca- 
demie  des  Sciences  et  les  Academi- 
ciens,'  p.  113).  See  also  Voltaire's 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


135 


system  was  the  old  Academy  of  Sciences,  which,  with 
a  short  interruption  during  the  storm  of  the  Eevolution, 
survived,1  and  formed  the  principal  feature  in  the  Insti- 
tute. Allied  with  this  institution,  and  directly  inspired 
by  its  spirit,  were  the  great  schools  of  natural  science,  the 
great  collections  of  natural  objects,  latterly  also  the  great 
medical  institutions  of  Paris.  It  professed  to  protect 
scientific  studies  in  a  royal  and  generous  manner,  at- 
tracted talent  from  outside,  rewarded  foreign  as  well  as 
French  research,2  and  tried  to  keep  the  scientific  spirit 
of  inquiry,  as  well  as  the  form  in  which  it  found 
expression,  pure  and  undefiled.3  It  favoured  the  co- 


'  Siecle  de  Louis  XIV.';  Cabanis, 
'  Revolutions  de  la  Medecine ' 
((Euvres,  Paris,  1823,  vol.  i.  p.  200); 
Flourens,  '  Eloges  historiques,'  vol. 
iii.  p.  31,  &c.  ;  Maury,  '  Les  Aca- 
demies d'autrefois,'  vol.  i.  p.:  153, 
163  et  passim;  Bouillier,  'Eloges 
de  Fontenelle,'  Introduction. 

1  "  Tandis  que  tout  a  ete  renou- 
vele  dans  la  politique  et  les  mocurs 
publiques  ...    la  vie  scientifique 
et  litttiraire  a  sensiblement  garde  sa 
constitution.    .    .    .    Le  College  de 
France,  1'Academie  francaise,  1'Aca- 
demie   des    Inscriptions   et   Belles- 
lettres,  1'Academie  des  Sciences,  la 
Bibliotheque   irnperiale,    1'Observa- 
toire,  le  Museum  d'Histoire  natur- 
elle,   subsistent  encore,   comme   au 
siecle  dernier,  et  dans  nos  provinces, 
une  foule   d'academies   sont    d'une 
creation  anterieure  a  1789"  (Maury, 
loc.  cit.,  p.  1). 

2  "  Euler  f  ut  quatre  fois  couronne 
pour  des  questions  de  physique  et 
de  mathematiques.    .     .     .     Daniel 
Bernoulli   obtint   le  prix  dix  fois" 
(Maury,, p.  171).     Among  the  cele- 
brated Eloges  by  Fonteuelle  there 
are  those  of  Leibniz,  of  Peter  the 
Great,  of  Newton,  of  Marsigli,  of 
Boerhaave  ;   among  those  by  Con- 


dorcet  there  are  those  of  Haller, 
Linnseus,  Hunter, and  Euler ;  among 
Cuvier's  there  are  those  of  Gilbert, 
Priestley,  De  Saussure,  Cavendish, 
Pallas,  Rumford,  Werner,  Banks, 
and  Davy. 

3  "Jusqu'a  present,"  says  Fon- 
tenelle in  1699,  "1'Academie  des 
Sciences  ne  prend  la  nature  que 
par  petites  parcelles.  Nul  systeme 
general,  de  peur  de  tomber  dans 
1'inconvenient  des  systemes  pre"ci- 
pites  dont  1'impatience  de  1'esprit 
huinain  ne  s'accommode  que  trop 
bien,  et  qui,  etant  une  fois  etablis, 
s'opposent  aux  verites  qui  survien- 
nent"  (quoted  by  Flourens,  'Eloges,' 
vol.  iii.  p.  19).  "  L'esprit  de  1'Acad- 
emie des  Sciences  a  done  toujours  ete 
1'esprit  d'experience,d'etude  directe, 
d'observation  precise,  1'amour  de  la 
certitude.  D'abord  cartesienne,  elle 
devint  ensuite  Newtonienne,"  &c. 
(ibid.,  p.  21).  Fontenelle  contrasts 
the  "  philosophic  ,des  mots  et  celle 
des  choses^de  1'Ecole  et  de  1'Aca- 
demie "  ('  Eloge  de  Du  Hamel '  in 
Bouillier,  p.  10).  "Fontenelle  se 
plait  a  multiplier  les  exemples  de 
cette  incapacite  chez  les  savants  de 
faire  fortune  et  de  ce  noble  des- 
interessement."  "  II  aitnait  mieux 


136 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


SO. 

Cuvier  the 
greatest 
representa- 
tive of  the 
Academic 
system. 


operation  of  many  minds  in  rearing  the  great  edifice  of 
science,  and  found  a  place  for  the  minutest  research,  as 
well  as  a  field  for  the  development  and  sway  of  great  and 
governing  ideas.  Of  the  best  form  of  this  spirit  and 
system — the  Academic — Cuvier  was  the  greatest  repre- 
sentative. Through  several  dozen  filoges  which  he  pro- 
nounced on  the  decease  of  a  number  of  the  most  illus- 
trious scientific  men  of  Europe,  as  well  as  through 
several  Reports,  in  which  he  summed  up  the  labours  and 
progress  of  his  age,  and  the  peculiar  features  of  his  period, 
he  affords  to  the  student  of  history  an  insight  into  that 
distinctive  phase  which  scientific  thought  had  entered  in 
France  at  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century.  This  he 
allows  us  to  contrast  with  other  phases  of  thought,  such 
as  the  philosophical  or  individual,  which  obtained  in  other 
ages  or  countries,  and  suggests  as  well  as  gives  the  means  of 
answering  the  question,  to  what  extent  the  scientific  ideal 


etudier  que  subsister,"  he  said  of 
one  of  the  Academicians  (Bouillier, 
pp.  ix,  xii).  Cuvier  was  very  watch- 
ful over  the  Academy  in  keeping 
out  the  speculative  spirit.  See 
what  he  says  in  the  joint  Report 
on  geology  with  Haiiy  and  Lelievre 
('  Mem.  de  I'lnstitut,'  vol.  viii.  1607, 
p.  136).  "  Que  doivent  done  faire 
les  corps  savans  pour  procurer  a  une 
science  aussi  interessante  et  aussi 
utile,  les  accroissemens  dont  elle  est 
susceptible  ?  ...  Us  doivent  tenir 
la  conduite,  qu'ils  ont  tenue  depuis 
leur  etablissement,  a  1'egard  de 
toutes  les  autres  sciences  :  encour- 
ager  de  lews  eloges  ceux  qui  con- 
statent  des  faits  positifs  et  garder 
un  silence  absolu  sur  les  systemes 
qui  se  succedent."  Compare  with 
this  what  he  says  about  the  use  of 
the  principle  of  "vital  force,"  al- 
ways referring  to  Xewton's  method 


('Me"m.  de  1'Inst.,'  vol.  vii.  p.  77, 
&c.),  further  in  his  analysis  of  Gall 
and  Spurzheim's  Memoire  ('  Mem. 
de  1'Inst.,'  vol.  ix.  p.  65):  "Les 
commissaires  de  la  classe  .  .  .  ont 
donne1  leur  assentiment  a  presque 
toutes  les  propositions  de  MM.  G. 
&  S.,  qui  ne  dependent  que  de 
^inspection  anatomique,  &c.  .  .  . 
les  commissaires  ont  cru  egale- 
ment  de  leur  devoir  de  prevenir  le 
public,  qu'il  n'y  a  aucun  rapport 
direct,  aucune  liaison  necessaire 
entre  ces  decouvertes  et  le  doctrine 
enseignee  par  MM.  G.  &  S.,  &c.  .  .  . 
Toutes  ces  matieres  sont  encore  trop 
etrangeres  aux  attributions  de  la 
classe,  elles  tiennent  aux  faits  sen- 
sibles  d'une  maniere  trop  lache, 
elles  pretent  a  trop  de  discussions 
vagues,  pour  qu'un  corps  tel  que 
le  notre  doive  s'en  occuper"  (p. 
159). 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT  JN   FRANCE. 


137 


of  the  end  of  this  century  agrees  with  or  differs  from  that 
of  its  beginning.  Upholding  the  Newtonian  rather  than 
the  Baconian  and  Leibnizian  standard  in  the  mathemati- 
cal and  physical  sciences,1  he  has  marked  that  line  which 
our  whole  century  has  contributed  to  trace  out  more  dis- 
tinctly ;  whilst,  as  regards  the  purely  natural  sciences,  his 
continued  emphasising  of  the  great  problem  of  organisation, 
and  his  later  controversy  with  Geoffrey  de  Saint-Hilaire, 
mark  that  point  in  which  this  century  has  most  distinctly 
departed  from  the  prevailing  ideas  of  its  early  years.2 
He  also  recognised  earlier  than  any  other  mind  of  similar 
eminence  what  our  century  increasingly  realises,  how, 
without  a  system  of  condensation,  contained  in  reports, 
statistics,  and  figures,  aided  by  classifications  and  systems, 
the  growing  bulk  of  accumulated  knowledge  becomes 
chaotic  and  unmanageable.3 


1  Cuvier  was  not  brought  up  in 
the  school  of  the  Encyclopaedists, 
and  I  cannot  find  that  he  attached 
the  great  importance  to  the  writ- 
ings of  Bacon  which  that  school 
commonly  did.  As  to  Newton  and 
Leibniz,  he  contrasts  their  methods, 
considering  them  "  comme  les  chefs 
et  les  representans  des  deux 
me'thodes  opposees  qui  se  sont  dis- 
pute 1'empire  de  la  science"  ('His- 
toire  des  Sciences  naturelles,' 
publiee  par  Magdeleine  de  Saiut- 
Agy,  Paris,  1841,  vol.  iii.  p.  19, 
&c. )  See  also  in  his  joint  Report 
with  Haiiy  and  Lelievre  on  the 
Science  of  Geology  ('  Mem.  de  Tin- 
stitut,'  1807,  p.  133):  "On  vit 
renaitre  dans  cette  partie  de  1'his- 
toire  naturelle  la  mdthode  systema- 
tique  de  Descartes,  que  Newton 
eemblait  avoir  bannie  pour  jamai.s 
de  toutes  les  sciences  physiques, 
.  .  .  et  lorsqu'on  songe  que  Leib- 
niz et  Buffon  sont  au  nombre 


des  philosophes  dont  je  parle  ici," 
&c. 

2  A  future  chapter  will  deal  speci- 
ally with  this  subject.     Cuvier,  as 
is  well  known,  maintained  the  fixity 
of  species,  and  opposed  the  theories 
of  St  Hilaire  and  Lamarck,  in  which 
a   later  generation   recognises   the 
beginnings  of  the  Darwinian  doc- 
trine of  the  transmutation  of  species. 
"On  est  oblige  d'admettre  certaines 
formes,    qui    se    sont     perpe'tue'es 
depuis    1'origine    des    choses,    sans 
exceder    ces    limites ;    et    tous    les 
etres  appartenans   a  1'une   de   ces 
formes     constituent    ce    que    Ton 
appelle   une   espece"  ('Regne  ani- 
mal,' vol.  i.  p.  20). 

3  Cuvier  was  the  first  great  scien- 
tific writer  who  undertook  to  give 
a  historical  survey  of  the  position 
of    the   different   natural   sciences, 
with  a  view  of  ascertaining  what 
had   been   achieved   and   what  re- 
mained to  be  done.     He  did  what 


138  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

Cuvier  had  also  a  true  historical  sense,  which  enabled 

him   to   trace   the  connection   of   science  with  political 

history,  with   literature,  with  the  fine  and  useful   arts. 

si.        And  he  helps  to  answer  a  question  which  to  us  is  of 

fortunes  of    paramount  interest,   How   did   science  fare    during   the 

science  dur- 
ing the  Re-    great  cataclysm  of  the  Eevolution  ?  how  under  the  reac- 

volutionand  °  • 

tionary  despotism  of  the  First  Empire  ?  Before  attempt- 
ing to  reply  to  these  questions  in  the  light  of  subse- 
quent and  general  European  history,  I  will  select  a  few 
passages  from  Cuvier  which  throw  light  upon  these 
points : 1 — 

"  There  is  always  a  revolution  required  in  order  to 
change  habits  which  have  become  general,  and  the  most 
necessary  revolutions  do  not  take  place  without  some 
circumstance,  which  is  sometimes  long  delayed.  "We 
have  been  able  to  see  how  in  such  a  case  everything 
furthers  the  sciences,  even  the  delays  and  contrarieties 
which  they  seem  to  suffer  under. 

"  The  events  which  disturbed  the  world,  and  which  for 
natural  science  temporarily  dried  up  the  sources  of  its 
riches,2  obliged  it  to  return  to  itself,  and  to  make  a  new 

study  of  what  it  possessed,  more  fruitful  than  the  most 

\ 

a  generation  later  the  British  Asso-  it  of  foreign  imports  and  the  scien- 

ciation  undertook  to  do,  and  what  tific  collections  of  foreign  specimens ; 

in    Germany    the    many    "Jahres-  see  also  'Eloges,'  vol.  i.  p.  9  ;  vol.  iii. 

berichte"  do   nowadays.      See   his  p.    202:     "Quand   la  jalousie   des 

"  Analyse  des  Travaux,"  &c., '  Mem.  peuples   nous  privait  des  produits 

de  1'Institut,'  vol.  ix.  p.  53,  and  his  etrangers,  la  chimie  les  faisait  eclore 

celebrated  'Rapport  historique  sur  de    notre    sol."       "  Le    conseil    des 

le  Progres  des  Sciences  naturelles  mines  ctabli  en  1793,  lorsque  1'in- 

depuis  1789,' Paris,  1810.  terruption    de    tout    rapport    avec 

1  '  Eloges  historiques, '  vol.  iii.  p.  1'etranger  fit    seutir   le   besoin   de 
456,  1824.  tirer    parti    de    notre    territoire    a 

2  This  refers  to  the  isolation   of  doune  k   ces    sortes    de    recherches 
France  during  the  war  and  the  Con-    '•   une     impulsion     toute     nouvelle" 
tinental  blockade,  which  deprived   i    ('  Piapport,'  p.   178). 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


139 


fortunate  departures  could  have  been.  During  this  ap- 
parent rest,  all  the  different  parts  of  method  were  deep- 
ened ;  the  interior  of  natural  objects  was  studied ;  even 
minerals  were  dissected  and  reduced  to  their  mechanical 
elements ;  a  still  more  intimate  analysis  was  made  by  a 
perfected  chemistry ;  the  earth  itself  was,  during  this 
interval,  if  the  expression  is  allowable,  dissected  by  the 
geologists ;  its  depths  were  sounded  ;  the  order  and  layers 
of  rock  which  form  its  shell  were  recognised.1  In  the 
absence  of  foreign  contributions  the  interior  of  the  soil 
on  which  we  walk  became  tributary  to  science.  The 
beings  of  which  it  contains  the  remains  came  to  light, 
and  revealed  a  natural  history  anterior  to  that  of  to- 
day, different  in  its  forms,  and  nevertheless  subject  to 
similar  laws,  thus  giving  to  these  laws  a  sanction  which 
no  one  expected.  The  botanists  did  not  gather  so  many 
plants  in  their  collections,  but  with  the  lens  in  hand  they 
demonstrated  more  and  more  the  intimate  structure  of 
the  fruit,  the  seed,  the  various  relations  which  connect 
the  parts  of  the  flower,  and  the  indications  which  these 
relations  furnish  for  a  natural  division.  The  most  deli- 
cate forms  of  organic  tissues  were  exhibited :  medicine 


1  Cuvier  refers  here  to  the  inves- 
tigation of  the  fossils  in  the  Paris 
basin,  which  he  undertook  during 
the  years  1804  to  1808  :  "  La  singu- 
larity des  animaux  clout  je  decouv- 
rais  les  ossements  a  Montmartre 
me  fit  desirer  de  connaitre  plus  en 
detail  la  composition  geologique  des 
environs  de  Paris.  Mon  ami  Brong- 
niart  s'associa  a  moi  pour  ce  travail ; 
nous  fimes  ensemble  et  separement 
beaucoup  de  courses.  .  .  .  Ces 
recherches  out  donne  une  face  toute 
nouvelle  a  la  geologic,  et  ont  occa- 


sionnd  toutes  celles  qu'ont  faites 
ensuite  en  Angleterre  MM.  Webster, 
Buckland,  Labeche  et  autres " 
(Cuvier,  "Mem.  sur  sa  Vie"  in 
Flourens,  '  Eloges,' vol.  iii.  p.  188). 
This  was  the  beginning  of  the 
Science  of  Palaeontology,  a  term 
which  Cuvier  did  not  use  himself 
(Flourens,  '  Travaux  de  Cuvier,'  p. 
147).  See  also  Cuvier,  '  Recherches 
sur  les  Ossemens  fossils  de  Quadru- 
pedes,'  &c.,  1st  ed.,  1812,  3rd  ed., 
1825,  in  the  Introduction. 


140  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

and  chemistry  united  their  efforts  to  appreciate  in  the 
minutest  detail  the  action  of  external  elements  on  the 
living  organism.1  The  different  combinations  of  organs, 
or  what  we  call  the  different  classes,  the  different  genera, 
were  not  less  studied  than  general  theories.  There  were 
no  animals,  ever  so  small,  the  inner  parts  of  which, 
unveiled  by  anatomy,  did  not  become  known  as  well 
as  our  own.  Every  organic  system  was  likewise  sub- 
mitted to  a  special  examination.  The  brain,  marking 
the  degree  of  intellectual  power;  the  teeth,  signs  of 
the  nature  and  energy  of  the  digestive  forces ;  the  bony 
system,  above  all,  which  is  the  support  of  all  others, 
and  which  determines  the  connected  forms  of  animals, 
— all  these  were  followed  into  the  smallest  species  and 
into  the  minutest  parts.  We  see  how,  after  such  studies, 
there  could  be  no  more  talk  of  superficial  or  artificial 
methods.  The  old  natural  history  had  ceased  to  rule. 
It  was  not  that  old  natural  history  any  more,  but  a 
science  full  of  life  and  youth,  armed  with  quite  novel 
ways  and  means,  which  beheld  the  world  reopened  by 
the  Peace."2 

In  an  earlier  passage,3  speaking  of  the  reopening  of 
academies  and  schools  by  the  Government  of  the  Eevolu- 


1  Compare  with  this  the  'Rap- 
port' of  the  year  1808,  p.  201,  &c. 
The  above  remarks  refer  mainly  to 
Bichat.  "Bichat  a  dorme"  a  1'ana- 
tomie  un  grand  inteYet,  par  1'opposi- 
tion  de  structure  et  de  forme  qu'il 
a  deVeloppde,  entre  les  organes  de 
la  vie  animale,  c'est-a-dire,  du  senti- 
ment et  du  mouvement,  et  ceux  de 
la  vie  purement  ve'ge'tative.  .  .  . 
L'attention  particuliere  donnee  par 
Bichat  au  tissu  et  aux  fonctions  des 
diverses  membranes,  et  1'analogie 


qu'il  a  etablie  entre  celles  de  parties 
tres  eloignees,  ont  jete  aussi  des 
lumieres  nouvelles  sur  1'anatomie, 
principalement  dans  ses  rapports 
avec  la  medecine"  ('Rapport,'  p. 
218). 

2  This  refers  to  the  peace  which 
concluded  the  Napoleonic  wars,  and 
re-established  the  free  intercourse 
of  France  with  ,the  rest  of  the  world. 

3  In   the   '  Eloge   of   Fourcroy," 
of  the  year  1811  ('Eloges,'  vol.  ii. 
p.  40,  &c.) 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   FRANCE. 


141 


tion,  Cuvier  remarks :  "  It  was  not  merely  a  question  of 
isolated  discoveries,  but  of  institutions,  which,  in  assuring 
the  conservation  of  the  sciences,  would  multiply  their 
progress  indefinitely.  What  was  needed  was  no  longer  a 
simple  experimenter,  master  of  his  subject  and  his  instru- 
ments, it  was  a  man  obliged  to  battle  against  all  kinds  of 
obstacles,  and  to  benefit  his  fellow-citizens,  mostly  in  spite 
of  themselves.  The  Convention  had  destroyed  academies, 
colleges,  universities ;  nobody  would  have  dared  to  ask 
boldly  for  their  restitution ;  but  soon  the  effects  of  their 
suppression  showed  themselves  in  the  most  susceptible 
point ;  the  armies  were  without  doctors  and  surgeons, 
and  these  could  not  be  created  without  schools.1  But 
who  would  believe  that  time  was  required  to  give  courage 
enough  to  call  them  schools  of  medicine.  Doctor  and 
surgeon  were  titles  too  contrary  to  equality,  apparently 
because  there  is  no  authority  over  the  patient  more  neces- 
sary than  that  of  the  doctor;  therefore  the  odd  term 
"  schools  of  health  "  was  used,  and  there  was  no  question 
of  either  examination  or  diploma  for  the  students.  In 
spite  of  this,  a  penetrating  glance  reveals,  in  the  regula- 
tions which  were  carried,  the  intentions  of  him  (Fourcroy) 
who  drew  them  up.  The  three  great  schools  founded  at 


1  See  'Eloges,'  vol.  i.  p.  353. 
"  Cependant  les  gens  qui  avaient 
fait  toutes  ces  suppressions  eurent 
promptement  lieu  de  s'apercevoir 
que,  s'il  e"tait  a  la  rigueur  superflu 
d'apprendre  toute  autre  chose,  on 
ne  pouvait  guere  se  dispenser  d'ap- 
prendre la  me"decine.  Toute  la 
France  se  prdcipitait  aux  frontieres, 
et,  apres  des  prodiges  inouis  de 
denouement  et  de  valeur,  les  defen- 
seurs  de  la  patrie  ne  trouvaient 


aucun  secours  pour  leurs  blessures 
et  pour  leurs  maladies.  On  com- 
menga  done  par  1'eYection  des  e"coles 
de  medecine  cette  longue  suite  de 
restaurations,  que  l'e"tablissement 
de  1'universite"  vient  de  couronner 
et  de  Her  en  un  ensemble  aussi 
imposant  par  1'etendue  de  son  plan 
que  par  la  vigueur  de  son  organisa- 
tion." See  also  'Rapport,'  &c.,  p. 
360. 


142  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

this  epoch,1  received  an  abundance  of  means,  of  which 
up  to  that  time  there  was  no  idea  in  France,  and  which 
still  form  the  finest  ornament  of  the  University." 

Similar  passages  might  Ira  collected  in  which  Cuvier 
enlarges  on  the  influence  of  war  and  revolutions,  of  the 
Continental  blockade  and  the  isolation  of  the  country  ;  on 
the  reconstruction  of  hospitals  and  the  admission  of  medi- 
cal science  into  the  Academy ;  on  the  creation  of  new 
industries ;  on  the  development  of  the  mining  and  mineral 
wealth  of  the  country ;  on  the  scientific  value  of  colonies 
and  travels,  and  many  other  interesting  topics.  In  con- 
fining myself  more  closely  to  the  history  of  thought  and 
the  growth  of  the  modern  scientific  spirit,  I  will  make 
some  reflections  which  his  remarks  force  upon  us. 
32.  I  have  noted  above  how  France  more  than  any  other 

doneCmore3    country  worked  for  the  popularisation  of  science,  how  her 

than  other 

countries  to  polite  literature  alone  during  the  eighteenth  century  bears 
science.  £ne  strong  impress  of  modern  scientific  ideas ;  no  other 
country  has  a  Fontenelle,  a  Voltaire,  a  Buffon.  This 
peculiarity  must  be  recognised  as  a  very  powerful  and 
valuable  stimulus  to  the  growth  of  the  scientific  spirit. 
It  emanates  largely,  if  not  exclusively,  from  the  peculiar 
position  of  the  old  Academy  of  Science.  It  must,  how- 
ever, not  be  forgotten  that  it  was  not  a  popularisation  of 
the  kind  we  witness  nowadays. 

ss.  The  class  of  literature  which  in  our  age  spreads  broad- 

Difference  IT  •  •  1  0       • 

between  the  cast  the  discoveries  or  ideas  of  science :  the  endless  num- 

literary  and 

theSfatrisaal  ^)er  °^  magazmes>  reviews,  and  daily  papers;  the  small 
treatises,  the  cheap  primers,  the  compact  text-books,  did 

1  They  were  the  three  "  Ecoles  de   '   struction  publique  en  France,' vol. 
Sante  "  at  Paris,  Strasbourg,  and       ii.  p.  194). 
Montpellier   (see    Hippeau,    '  L'ln- 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE.  143 

not  then  exist.1  Science  was  not  a  subject  of  general,  still 
less  of  popular,  instruction.  It  was  an  occupation  of  the 
few,  who,  privileged  by  fortune  or  talent,  or  gifted  with 
inordinate  perseverance,  forced  their  way  into  the  salons 
of  society2  or  the  rooms  of  the  Academy.  The  first  public 
course  of  natural  history  was  opened  in  Paris  by  Valmont 
de  Bomare  in  1 7 6 O.3  Science  still  stood  far  out  of  the  reach 
of  the  practical  man  or  the  poor  man ;  it  had  not  yet 
become  an  element  of  education  or  an  instrument  for 
industry.  It  was  a  fashionable  pursuit,  a  luxury  of  the 
great,  a  key  that  occasionally  opened  the  door  of  the 
palace ;  but  it  was  not  a  thing  of  immediate  use,  except 
in  adding  glory  and  renown  to  its  royal  protectors,  or 
to  the  rare  genius  which  could  make  new  discoveries. 
Almost  the  only  application  made  of  it  was  in  naviga- 
tion, and  in  the  construction  of  instruments  connected 
therewith.  This  essentially  literary — not  national — 
popularisation  of  science  had  also  its  great  dangers.  34. 
No  ideas  lend  themselves  to  such  easy,  but  likewise  to  the  merely 

literary  pop- 

such  shallow,  generalisations  as  those  of  science.  Once 
let  out  of  the  hand  which  uses  them,  in  the  strict  and 
cautious  manner  by  which  alone  they  lead  to  valuable 
results,  they  are  apt  to  work  mischief.  Because  the  tool 
is  so  sharp,  the  object  to  which  it  is  applied  seems  to  be 


1  Cuvier,  in  his  '  Rapport,'  &c.,  p. 
361,  mentions  the  elementary  works 
published  by  some  of  the  medical 
professors  at  the  beginning  of  the 


-  See  Maury,  p.  182,  &c.  Also  Cu- 
vier, '  Rapport,'  vol.  ii.  p.  427  :  "En 
France  la  reputation  des  ouvrages 
depend,  pour  1 'ordinaire,  des  femmes 


century,   but  says   also   that  "  En   j    et  de  quelques  gens  de  lettres,  qui 


Allemagne,  surtout,  ou  1'usage  des 
livres  olcmentaires  est  plus  cornmun 
que  chez  nous,  il  n'est  presque 
aucune  universite",  dont  les  profes- 
seurs  n'en  aient  public  d'excel- 
leus." 


croient  pouvoir  juger  des  sciences 
positives,  parce  qu'ils  ont  combine" 
quelques  ide'es  gdnerales  de  me"ta- 
physique." 

3  See  Maury,  '  L'ancienne  Acad- 
dmie  des  Sciences,'  p.  283. 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


so  easily  handled.  The  correct  use  of  scientific  ideas  is 
only  learned  by  patient  training,  and  should  be  governed 
by  the  not  easily  acquired  habit  of  self-restraint.  It  is 
well  known  how  the  fundamental  notions  of  a  mechanical 
science,  let  loose  into  literature  by  Fontenelle,  by  D'Alem- 
bert,  by  Condorcet,  or  absorbed  by  Voltaire  and  Diderot, 
were  expanded  into  a  system  of  materialistic  philosophy 
in  '  L'Homme  Machine,'  the  '  Systeme  de  la  Nature,'  and 
other  works,  the  extreme  views  of  which  the  great  scien- 
tific thinkers  could  hardly  approve  of.1  These  hasty  but 


1  As  a  great  deal  of  confusion  ex- 
isted for  a  long  time  in  European 
literature  as  to  the  exact  succession 
in  time  of  the  different  works  which 
assisted  to  spread  mechanical  views 
of  the  world  and  of  life,  I  put  down 
the  main  dates  : — 

Fontenelle  (1657-1757)  published 
his  Eloges  of  the  great  Academi- 
cians, in  which  the  principles  of 
the  philosophy  of  Descartes,  Leib- 
niz, and  Newton  were  popularly 
expounded  and  discussed,  from 
1700  onward.  His  '  Pluralite  des 
Mondes'  had  appeared  already  in 
1686  ;  it  had 'popularised  Cartesian 
ideas. 

Vol,taire  (1694-1778)  published 
his  '  Ele'mens  de  la  Philosophic  de 
Newton'  in  1738. 

La  Mettrie  (1709-51)  published 
his  '  Histoire  naturelle  de  1'Ame ' 
in  1745,  and  his  '  L'Homme 
Machine'  in  1748. 

D'Alembert  and  Diderot  pub- 
lished the  first  volume  of  the  '  En- 
cyclopedic' in  1751. 

Buffon  (1707-88)  published,  1749, 
his  '  Thforie  de  la  Terre,'  being  the 
first  portion  of  the  '  Histoire  natur- 
elle.' 

Holbach  (1723-89)  published 
under  the  name  of  Mirabaud, 
1770,  the  'Systeme  de  la  Nature.' 

Of  these  works,  the  three  which 


created  the  greatest  popular  sensa- 
tion—  viz.,  Voltaire's  '  Elemens,' 
La  Mettrie's  '  L'Homme  Machine,' 
j  and  Holbach's  '  Systeme ' — were  all 
published  in  Holland.  Voltaire, 
D'Alembert,  and  Diderot  appear  to 
|  have  approached  philosophical  prob- 
i  lems  mainly  from  the  position  of 
J  Newton's  natural  philosophy,  La 
Mettrie  from  the  teachings  of  the 
great  Boerhaave,  Holbach  princi- 
pally from  a  study  of  chemistry. 
It  is  unnecessary  to  say  that  none 
of  them  had  the  sanction  of  their 
great  masters  for  the  applications 
they  made  of  principles  which  had 
been  established  and  used  for  special 
scientific  purposes.  And  the  same 
may  be  said  with  reference  to  the 
influence  of  Locke,  which  in  almost 
all  the  instances  mentioned  was 
combined  with  that  of  the  great 
naturalists.  But  this  does  not  be- 
long to  the  line  of  thought  in  which 
we  are  interested  at  present.  For 
the  sake  of  completeness  only  I 
mention  that  Locke's  teachings  as 
well  as  Newton's  were  made  popu- 
larly known  in  France  by  Voltaire's 
"  Lettres  sur  les  Anglais '  (burnt  by 
order  of  the  Parliament  of  Paris  in 
1734),  whereas  Condillac's  (1714-80) 
more  systematic  treatise,  entitled 
'Essaisurl'OriginedesConnaissances 
humaines,'  appeared  in  1746.  It  is 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN    FRANCE. 


145 


brilliant  generalisations,  expressed  frequently  in  the  most 
perfect  language,  did  no  good  to  the  truly  scientific  cause  ; 
they  did  not  spread  the  genuine  scientific  spirit.  Much 
of  the  good  done  by  Fontenelle,  by  Voltaire,  by  Buffon, 
was  spoiled  or  neutralised  by  premature  and  ill-founded 
theories.  How  much,  or  how  little,  they  contributed 
(either  directly  or  by  a  kind  of  reaction  which  set  in 
against  them,  of  which  Eousseau  may  be  regarded  as  the 
centre)  to  bring  about  the  Eevolution  is  a  matter  of 
much  controversy ;  certain  it  is  that  the  Eevolution 
broke  their  sway,  and  destroyed  their  immediate  influ- 
ence.1 To  the  purely  literary  the  Eevolution  added 


important,  in  dealing  with  the  ex- 
treme materialistic  writings  which 
French  literature  produced  between 
1745  and  1770,  to  keep  distinct  the 
different  origins  from  which  they 
started,  and  the  different  influences 
which  combined  to  produce  them  : 
the  mathematical  and  mechanical 
principles  borrowed  from  Newton, 
the  physiological  and  medical  eman- 
ating from  Linnrcus  and  Boerhaave, 
and  the  psychological  coming  from 
Locke  and  Shaftesbury.  Lange,  in 
his '  History  of  Materialism '  (transl. 
by  Thomas,  London,  1880,  3  vols.), 
was  the  first  to  point  out  clearly  the 
correct  chronology  and  succession 
of  these  writings  (see  especially  vol. 
ii.  pp.  49-123),  and  to  dispel  the 
misconceptions  which,  since  the  ap- 
pearance of  Hegel's  '  Geschichte  der 
Philosophic'  in  1833-36,  had  passed 
through  nearly  all  historical  works 
published  in  Germany.  From  his 
exhaustive  references,  it  is  evident 
that  the  extreme  views  of  La 
Mettrie,  Diderot,  and  Holbach  can- 
not be  fathered  on  any  of  the  great 
scientists  or  philosophers,  but  were 
an  attempt  to  apply  scientific  prin- 
ciples to  the  solution  of  philosophi- 
cal, ethical,  or  religious  questions, 

VOL.  I. 


frequently  for  practical  and  politi- 
cal purposes. 

1  It  would  probably  be  more 
correct  to  say  that  these  daring 
attempts  to  deal  with  the  general 
problems  of  knowing  and  being, 
with  the  nature  of  the  soul  and  the 
conduct  of  life,  were  discarded  as 
premature,  and  that  the  followers 
of  Condillac  and  Locke  betook  them- 
selves to  a  more  patient  study  of 
the  facts  of  the  inner  life,  as  the 
followers  of  Buffon  forsook  his  bril- 
liant generalisations  for  the  more 
patient  and  fruitful  study  of  all 
the  forms  of  physical  nature.  And 
in  this  respect  the  Government  of 
the  Revolution  took  a  memorable 
step  when  it  founded  on  the  3rd 
brumaire,  an  iv.  (25th  October 
1795),  on  a  Report  of  Daunou, 
based  mainly  on  ideas  expounded 
by  Condorcet,  the  "Academic  des 
Sciences  morales  et  politiques."  It 
was  the  intention  to  abandon  meta- 
physical generalisations,  and  to  com- 
bine the  scientific  and  historical 
spirit  in  the  study  of  mental, 
moral,  and  social  phenomena,  draw- 
ing extensively  on  the  assistance  of 
the  medical  sciences,  or  a  know- 
ledge of  human  nature  in  its  nor- 

K 


35 

The  Revolu- 
tion added 
the  modern 
practical 
popularisa- 
tion of 
science. 


146  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

something  different — viz.,  the  modern  practical  popular- 
isation of  science :  it  established  its  educational  and  its 
technical  importance.  Science  was  to  be  not  an  elegant 
amusement,  or  a  refined  luxury,  nor  even  exclusively 
the  serious  occupation  of  the  rare  genius :  it  was  to  be 
the  basis  of  a  national  instruction,  and  the  foundation 
of  the  greatness  and  wealth  of  the  nation.  The  Memoirs 
of  the  Academy  were  cleansed  of  all  dangerous  general- 
isations which  might  have  brought  them  into  touch  with 
political  controversy ;  the  language  was  confined  to  the 
measured  and  concise  statement  of  facts,  or  to  theories 
capable  of  mathematical  verification  and  treatment :  con- 
jectural matter  was  carefully  excluded,  and  a  standard  of 
scientific  excellence,  both  in  matter  and  form,  was  raised, 
to  which  we  still  look  up  with  admiration.1  At  the  same 
time,  this  lofty  and  dignified  spirit  enlivened  the  cou: 

mal  and  diseased  conditions.  This  ne  se  rendre  qu'a  des  calculs  ou  a  ties 
organisation  produced,  during  its  experiences  positives  "(vol.  iii.  p.  12). 
short  existence  of  only  seven  years,  Compare  also  ;  Mem.  de  Flnstitut,' 

voL  vii.  p.   77,  where  he  speaks  of 


some  memorable  works ;  but  its 
position  was  for  various  reasons 
secondary  only :  it  was  eclipsed  by 
the  European  renown  which  the 


the  method  of  Newton,  showing 
how  little  the  employment  of  a 
principle  like  that  of  "  vital  force '' 


"  Academic  des  Sciences  "  possessed,  in  physiology  can  be  compared  with 
owing  to  its  historical  antecedents  ;   that   of  gravitation,   employed   by 

and  its  brilliant  discoveries  and  the  Newton  to  explain  the  movement 

practical  usefulness  of  its  labours.  of  the  heavenly  bodies ;  again,  vol. 

But  the  idea  of  including  ethical  viii.  p.  139,  where  he  refers  to  the 

and  political  studies  under  the  term  great  service  rendered  by  the  Aca- 

"  Science,"   due   probably  to   Con-  demy,  li  s?il  parvenait  a  diriger  les 

dorcet,  was  fixed  by  this  organisa-  esprits  vers  des  recherches  positives, 

tion,  and  has  in  the  course  of  the  mais   longues   et   penibles."      And 

century  acquired   increasing  influ-  vol.  ix.  p.  61 :  "  On  aime  toujours 

ence.     From  these   beginnings  we  a  voir  se  multiplier  dans  les  sciences 

shall  have  to  study  its  career  in  an-  experimen  tales  les  inoyens  simples 

other  portion  of  the  present  work.  d'arriver   h  la   precision    et    de   se 

1  According  to  Cuvier,  "  la  langue  rapprocher  des  sciences  mathema- 

naturelle  de   1' Academic    des    Sci-  tiques,"  and  other  passages  quoted 

ences"  is  "la  langue  des  chifires"'  above,  p.  115  and  p.  128.     See  also 

('Eloges,'  vol.  L  p.  24);  "1'Acade-  his  remarks  on  the  Philosophy  of 

mie  a  toujours  eu  pour  principe  de  Nature,   'Rapport,'  p.  335. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


147 


of  lectures  delivered  in  the  great  schools  by  the  first  men 
of  the  nation,  and  became,  through  them,  the  habit  of  a 
large  number  of  ardent  pupils,  who  were  to  carry  it  fur- 
ther into  more  popular  teaching,  or  into  the  applications 
of  art  and  industry.1  The  results  of  both  are  well  known. 
We  still  live,  at  the  end  of  the  century,  under  their  im- 
mediate influence.  If  now  we  continually  appeal  to  scien- 
tific authorities  for  aid  in  the  solution  of  practical  prob- 
lems, it  is  well  to  remember  that  nothing  helped  more  to 
raise  science  to  the  eminence  of  a  great  social  power  than 
the  action  of  the  Kevolutionary  Government  in  1793. 
Whilst  it  guillotined  Lavoisier,  Bailly,  and  Cousin  ;  drove 
Condprcet  to  suicide,  and  others  like  Vicq-d'Azyr  and 
Dionis  du  Sejour  into  premature  death ; 2  it  had  to  ap- 


1  See  Cuvier,  "  Reflexions  sur  les 
Sciences,"  1816,  in  '  Eloges,'  &c., 
vol.  i.  p.  24,  &c.  :  "  Que  1'on  re- 
cherche, ce  qu'oiit  valu  a  la  France 
depuis  vingt  ana  les  inventions 
pratiques  derivees  des  d^couvertes 
de  MM.  Berthollet,  Chaptal,  Vau- 
quelin,  Thenard,  &c. ,  dans  la  seule 
chimie  minerale,  dans  cette  branche 
assez  bornee  des  sciences  physiques  ; 
1'extraction  de  la  soude,  la  fabrica- 
tion de  1'alun,  du  sel  ammoniac,  des 
oxydes  de  plomb,  des  acides  mine- 
raux,  toutes  substances  que  nous 
tirions  de  1'etranger ;  1'epuration 
des  fers,  la  cementation  de  1'acier 
et  enfin  le  developpement  des  arts 
qui  emploient  ces  matieres  premi- 
eres :  il  est  clair  que  c'est  par  cen- 
taines  de  millions  qu'il  faudra  cal- 
culer."  Also,  vol.  iii.  p.  202  :  "  Les 
applications  de  la  science  a  la  pra- 
tique avaient  fait  de  M.  Berthollet, 
lorsque  la  guerre  de  la  revolution 
eclata,  le  chimiste  le  plus  connu  du 
public,  apres  Lavoisier  ;  et  il  etait 
presque  impossible  que  1'on  ne  re- 
couriit  pas  a  lui  au  moment  ou  la 


chimie  devint  pour  la  guerre  un 
auxiliaire  de  premiere  necessite",  et 
lorsqu'il  fallut  demander  a  notre 
sol  le  salpetre,  la  potasse  et  jus- 
qu'aux  rnati6res  colorantes ;  qu'il 
fallut  apprendre  a  faire  en  quelques 
jours  toutes  les  operations  des  arts. 
Chacun  se  souvieut  de  cette  prodi- 
gieuse  et  subite  activite  qui  etonna 
1'Europe,  et  arracha  des  eloges 
meme  aux  ennemis  qu'elle  arreta. 
M.  Berthollet  et  son  ami  M.  Monge 
en  furent  1'ame." 

2  Vicq-d'Azyr  (1748-94),  the  great 
forerunner  of  Cuvier  in  the  new 
science  of  comparative  anatomy, 
"  au  sortir  d'une  de  ces  parodies 
sinistres  de"corees  du  nom  de  fete 
nationale,  e'tait  saisi  d'un  mal  qui 
1'enlevait  en  quelques  instants  dans 
le  delire  de  la  peur.  Diouis  du 
Se'jour  (1734-94),  apres  deux  annees 
d'effroi  et  de  misere,  ne  trouvait 
plus  assez  de  force  pour  gouter  les 
temps  moins  malheureux  amenes 
par  la  chute  de  Robespierre " 
(Maury,  'Les  Academies  d'autre- 
fois,'  vol.  i.  p.  332). 


148  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

peal  for  its  most  necessary  requirements  to  the  society 
of  scientific  authorities,  which  it  professed  not  to  need. 
"  Everything,"  says  the  historian  of  the  Academy,1  "  was 
wanting  for  the  defence  of  the  country — powder,  cannons, 
provisions.  The  arsenals  were  empty,  steel  was  no  longer 
imported  from  abroad,  saltpetre  came  not  from  India.  It 
was  exactly  those  men  whose  labours  had  been  proscribed 
who  could  give  to  France  what  she  wanted.  Fourcroy, 
assisted  by  researches  begun  by  Lavoisier,  taught  the 
methods  of  extracting  and  refining  saltpetre ;  Guy  ton  de 
Morveau  and  Berthollet  made  known  a  new  method  of 
manufacturing  gunpowder,  and  studied  the  making  of 
iron  and  steel ;  Monge  explained  the  art  of  casting  and 
boring  cannons  of  brass  for  land  use,  and  cast-iron  cannons 
for  the  navy.  On  the  6th  of  August  1793  the  Conven- 
tion had  again  to  appeal  to  the  Academy  in  order  to  know 
what  advantage  it  would  be  to  refine  as  much  as  possible 
the  coins  of  the  Eepublic  ? "  In  the  space  of  a  few  years 
science  had  become  a  necessity  to  society  at  large.2  In  the 
Constitution  of  the  regenerated  Academies  it  was  placed  at 
the  head,  as  the  most  important  department  of  knowledge. 

1  Maury,  loc.  cit.,  vol.  i.  p.  329.    [  sion,   which   lasted   from  ..the    8th 

August  1793  till  the  22nd  August 
1795,  Lakanal  had  succeeded  in 
procuring  the  following  decree  from 


See  also  Biot's  '  Essai  sur  1'Histoire 
generate  des  Sciences  pendant  la 
Revolution  francaise.'  Paris,  1803. 
2  The  last  entry  in  the  record  of 
the  "proces-verbaux  de  1' Academic " 
before  the  suspension  was  a  Report 
by  Borda,  Laplace,  and  Lagrange, 
in  answer  to  a  demand  of  the  Con- 
vention, dated  19th  January  1793, 
for  advice  on  the  new  system  of 
weights  and  measures  which  the 
Republic  should  adopt.  And  so 
necessary  had  the  assistance  of  men 
of  science  become  to  the  Govern- 
ment, that  even  during  the  suspen- 


the Government  of  the  Convention : 
"La  Convention  nationale  decrete 
que  les  membres  de  la  ci-devant 
Acade~mie  des  Sciences  continueront 
de  s'assembler  dans  le  lieu  ordinaire 
de  leurs  seances,  pour  s'occuper 
specialement  des  objets  qui  leur 
auront  e"te  ou  pourront  leur  etre 
renvoye's  par  la  Convention  nation- 
ale"  (Maury,  loc.  cit.,  p.  331; 
Aucoc,  '  L'Institut  de  France,'  p. 
ccvii,  &c.) 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   FRANCE. 


149 


nce  of 


The  influence  of  the  first  Napoleon  on  science  is  natur-        se. 

Influen 

ally  a  matter  of  as  much  controversy  as  his  merit  in 
almost  every  branch  of  administration.      The  reports1  onscience 


1  According  to  a  decree  of  the 
Government,  dated  13th  ventose.  an 
x.  (4th  March  1802),  the  Institute, 
then  consisting  of  three  classes — 
the  "Academic  des  Sciences  phy- 
siques et  mathematiques,"  the 
"  Academic  des  Sciences  morales 
et  politiques,"  and  the  "Academic 
de  Litterature  et  Beaux -arts" — 
was  ordered  to  furnish  "  un  tableau 
de  1'etat  et  des  progres  des  sciences, 
des  lettres  et  des  arts,  depuis  1789 
jusqu'au  lre  venddmiaire  an  x." 
This  "tableau"  was  to  be  divided 
into  three  parts  according  to  the 
three  classes  of  the  Institute.  These 
Reports  were  to  be  repeated  every 
five  years.  The  first  (and  only) 
Reports  were  not  presented  before 
February  and  March  1808.  The 
Republican  Government  had  then 
been  superseded  by  the  Empire,  and 
by  a  decree  of  the  3rd  pluviose,  an 
xi.  (23rd  January  1803),  the  Institute 
had  been  reorganised.  There  were 
now  four  classes  :  1.  Des  Sciences 
physiques  et  mathematiques  (corre- 
sponding to  the  old  Academic  des 
Sciences).  2.  De  la  langue  et  de  la 
litterature  frangaises  (correspond- 
ing to  the  old  Academic  franchise). 
3.  D'histoire  et  de  litterature  auci- 
enne  (corresponding  to  the  "  Acad- 
emic d'Inscriptions  et  de  Belles- 
lettres").  4.  Des  beaux-arts.  "  On 
eupprima  la  classe  des  sciences 
morales  et  politiques  qui  existait 
dans  1'organisation  du  3  brumaire, 
an  iv.  Ce  fut  un  trait  caracteris- 
tique  de  la  repugnance  du  premier 
Consul  pour  la  discussion  des 
matieres  politiques  et  leur  enseigne- 
ment"  (Thibaudeau,'Le  Consulatet 
1'Empire,'  Paris,  1835-37,  vol.  iii.  p. 
396).  Accordingly  there  were  pre- 
pared four,  or  rather  five,  Reports, 
he  first  in  two  parts  by  Delambre 


and  Cuvier  on  the  progress  of  the 
Mathematical  and  Physical  Sciences ; 
the  second  by  Marie-Joseph  Chenier 
on  the  progress  of  Literature  ;  the 
third  by  Dacier  on  the  progress  of 
History  and  Classical  Literature ; 
the  fourth  by  Le  Breton  on  Fine 
Arts.  Of  these  the  two  Reports  of 
Delambre  and  Cuvier  gave  great 
satisfaction,  that  of  Dacier  gave  less 
satisfaction  ;  Chenier,  who  himself 
admired  the  eighteenth  -  century 
philosophy,  had  an  embarrassing  task 
to  perform,  of  which,  however,  he 
acquitted  himself  worthily  (Thibau- 
deau,  loc.  cit.,  vol.  vi.  p.  557).  The 
Report  of  Che'nier  has  been  several 
times  reprinted.  The  new  science 
which  was  founded  by  Condillac, 
Turgot,  Condorcet,  and  others,  and 
which  aimed  at  introducing  the  truly 
scientific  spirit  into  psychology,  psy- 
cho-physical researches,  and  ques- 
tions of  society  and  legislation,  re- 
ceived no  recognition,  as  it  had  also 
lost  its  representation  in  the  sus- 
pended "Academic  des  Sciences 
morales  et  politiques."  After  the 
re-establishment  of  this  section  of 
the  Institute  in  1832,  a  royal  decree 
of  22nd  March  1840  ordered  a  Re- 
port on  the  progress  of  the  Moral 
and  Political  Sciences  from  1789  to 
1832.  The  task  was  so  great  that 
it  could  not  be  accomplished  before 
the  Revolution  of  1848,  and  was 
therefore  abandoned  (Aucoc, '  L'ln- 
stitut  de  France,'  pp.  62  note,  300). 
Some  reference  to  the  subject  is 
contained  in  the  introduction  to 
Chenier's  Report,  and  in  the  last 
chapter  of  Dacier's,  which  was 
written  by  De  Gerando.  The  true 
history  of  the  new  science  has  been 
recently  written  by  F.  Picavet, 
'  Les  Ideologues,'  Paris,  1891. 


150  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

which  Delambre  and  Cuvier  drew  up  at  his  request, 
touching  the  progress  of  science  during  the  twenty  years 
which  followed  the  outbreak  of  the  Eevolution,  have 
become  classical  as  monuments  of  the  achievements  of  a 
great  age,1  and  as  examples  of  the  best  style  in  which  to 
treat  such  a  subject.  Written  immediately  under  his  eye, 
they  cannot  be  considered  quite  impartial,  so  far  as  the  tone 
is  concerned  in  which  they  refer  to  his  personal  favours 
and  protection.2.  There  can,  however,  be  no  doubt  that 
he  recognised  scientific  merit,  and  drew  many  eminent 
men  of  science  into  the  service  of  the  Government.  The 
institutions  on  which  he  prided  himself  so  much, — the 
£cole  Normale,  the  £cole  Polytechnique,  and  the  unfin- 
ished scheme  of  a  great  centralised  Institution  of  Learn- 
ing and  Education,  descending  from  the  heights  of  the 
Institute,  through  the  various  branches  of  the  higher  and 
secondary  into  a  multitude  of  primary  schools,  bearing 
the  name  of  the  "  University," — had  either  existed,  or 
been  planned  before  him.3 

1  Napoleon  in  discussing  at  the  i  miers  ;    le    3    fevr.    1808,    acconi- 
council  meeting  the  decree  which   j  pagnes  de  Bougainville,  president, 
ordered  the  several  reports,  said  to  !  et  des  doyens  de  toutes  les  sections. 
Regnaud  :  "Soignez  bien  cette  re-  La  ceremonie  fut  solennelle  ;  Fern- 
daction,  car  elle  sera  examinee  par  i  pereur   fit   une    belle  reponse,   qui 
les  pedagogues  de  toute  1'Europe"   I  est  imprimee  a  la  fin   du  rapport. 
(Thibaudeau,  loc.  cit.,  vol.  ii.  p.  496).   j  Je    sus   le   lendemain,    par   M.,   de 

2  See  what  Cuvier  himself  says   ,  Segur  et  d'autres  conseillers  d'Etat, 
on  this  subject  (Memoires,  &c.,  in   j  qu'il  avait  exprime  une  grande  satis- 


Flourens,  '  Eloges,'  vol.  iii.  p.  187) : 
"  Un  rapport  sur  le  progres  des 
sciences  devait  etre  presente  aux 
consuls  en  fructidor  an  xi.  .  .  . 
Ou  ne  fut  pret  qu'a  la  fin  de  1807  : 
ce  n'etait  plus  aux  consuls  mais  a 
1'einpereur  que  Ton  avait  a  pre- 
senter le  travail.  II  le  re?ut  avec 


faction  de  iiion  rapport  eii  parti- 
culier  :  '  II  m'a  loue  comme  j'aime  a 
1'etre,  dit-il.'  Cepeudant  je  m'etais 
borne  a  1'inviter  a  imiter  Alexan- 
dre  et  a  faire  tourner  sa  puissance 
au  profit  de  1'histoire  naturelle." 

3  Regarding  the  University,  see 
'  Code  Universitaire  ou  Lois,  Statuts 


un  grand  appareil  dans  la  seance  du  :  et  Reglemens  de  I'L'uiversite  Royale 
conseil  d'Etat.  M.  Delambre  et  de  France,  mis  en  ordre  par  M. 
nioi  presentames  le  notre  les  pre-  ;  Ambroise  Rendu,'  Paris,  1SS5.  In 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE. 


151 


37. 

Napoleon 


It  will  therefore  always  remain  a  matter  of  doubt  to 
what  extent  he  originated  ideas,  or  merely  adopted  those 
of  others  before  and  around  him.  He  favoured  the  mathe- 
matical sciences,  and  created  great  prizes  for  physical, 
notably  electrical,  discoveries,  partly  because  these  pursuits  M 
promised  to  surround  his  Government  with  glory,  partly 
because  he  recognised  their  practical  importance  for  the 
purposes  of  the  state  and  nation ;  partly  also,  because  he 
himself  had  had  a  mathematical  training.1  During  his 


the  Introduction  we  read  as  follows  : 
"  Bonaparte  passait  a  Turin.  Un 
jour  qu'il  mrcourait  le  palais  de 
1'Universite  fondee  en  1771  par 
Charles  Emmanuel  III.,  il  se  fit  re- 
presenter  les  statuts  qui  regissaient 
cette  institution.  II  y  vit  quelque 
chose  de  grand  et  de  fort  qui  le 
frappa.  .  .  .  Tout  ce  plan 
d'educatiou  etabli  sur  la  base  an- 
tique et  imperissable  de  la  foi  chre- 
tienne,  tout  cela  lui  plut,  et  il  en 
garda  la  meruoire  jusqu'au  sein  de 
ses  triomphes  en  Italic  et  en  Alle- 
inagne.  Rassasie  eufin  de  gloire 
militaire,  et  songeant  aux  geueYa- 
tions  futures,  apres  avoir  solidement 
etabli  1'administration  civile,  apres 
avoir  releve  les  autels  et  promulgue 
le  Code  Napoleon,  apres  avoir  par 
differentes  lois,  substitue  les  Lycees 
aux  Ecoles  Centrales,  regenere  les 
Ecoles  de  Medecine,  et  cred  les 
Ecoles  de  Droit,  il  voulut  fonder 
aussi  pour  la  France  un  systeme 
entier  destruction  et  d'education 
publique.  II  se  souvenait  de  1'uni- 
versite  de  Turin  et  1'agrandissant 
comme  tout  ce  qu'il  touchait,  dans 
la  double  proportion  de  son  empire 
et  de  son  genie,  il  fit  1'Universite 
imperiale." 

1  Among  many  references  relat- 
ing to  this  subject,  I  select  one  from 
Villemain,  '  Souvenirs  contempor- 
ains  d'Histoire  et  -de  Litterature,' 
•which  iu  the  first  volume  (9me  tkl., 


Paris,  1874,  p.  137)  contains,  the 
description  of  a  visit  to  the  Ecole 
Normale  in  1812,  and  a  discussion 
with  Narbonne,  to  whom  the  Em- 
peror had  fully  expressed  his  aims 
regarding  education  and  learn- 
ing. "  L'Empereur  n'est  inquiet 
que  d'une  chose  dans  le  monde,  les 
gens  qui  parlent,  et  a  leur  defaut 
les  gens  qui  pensent.  ...  II 
veut,  et  il  me  P»  dit  vingt  fois,  que 
son  regne  soit  signale  par  de  grands 
travaux  d'esprit,  de  grands  ouv- 
rages  litteraires.  Etre  loue  comme 
inspirateur  de  la  science  et  des  arts, 
etre  le  chef  eclatant  d'une  epoque 
glorieuse  pour  1'esprit  humain,  c'est 
1'idee  qui  le  flatte  le  plus  ;  c'est  ce 
qu'il  a  cherche  par  des  Prix  Decen- 
naux.  ...  II  veut  (a  PEcole 
Normale)  des  e"tudes  fortement  clas- 
siques,  1'autiquite  et  le  siecle  de 
Louis  XIV. ;  puis  quelques  elements 
de  sciences  mathe'matiques  et  plus 
tard  la  haute  ge"ometrie,  qui  est, 
dit-il,  le  sublime  abstrait,  comme  la 
grande  poesie,  la  grande  eloquence 
est  le  sublime  sensible."  Napoleon 
said  to  Narbonne:  "J'aime  les 
sciences  mathe'matiques  et  phy- 
siques ;  chacune  d'elles,  1'algebre, 
la  chimie,  la  botanique,  est  une 
belle  application  partielle  de  1'esprit 
humain ;  les  lettres,  c'est  1'esprit 
humain  lui-meme.  .  .  .  Aussi, 
j'aideux  ambitions :  Clever  la  France 
au  plus  haut  degre  de  la  puissance 


152 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


38. 

He  discoun- 


campaigns  in  Italy  and  Germany,  and  on  his  expeditions 
to  Egypt  and  the  East,  he  surrounded  himself  with  some 
of  the  greatest  scientific  authorities,  such  as  Berthollet 
and  Monge.  From  political  as  well  as  personal  motives, 
he  discountenanced  the  once  fashionable  sensualistic  phil- 
°^°pliy.  This  philosophy  has  now  fallen  to  the  second 
raQk,  though  still  represented  by  eminent  thinkers,  such 
Mophy-  as  Cabanis,  Destutt  de  Tracy,  Daunou  and  Garat.  It 
was  these  thinkers  of  whom  Xapoleon  sneeringly  spoke 
under  the  designation  of  "  Ideologues."  l 

After  all  that  has  been  said  by  admirers  to  magnify, 
and  by  opponents  to  minimise,  Xapoleon's  merits  in  pro- 
moting the  cause  of  science,  and  in  spreading  the  modern 
scientific  spirit,  I  cannot  but  recognise  that  he  was,  amongst 
the  great  heroes  and  statesmen  of  his  age,  the  first  and 
foremost,  if  not  the  only  one,  who  seemed  thoroughly  to 
realise  the  part  which  science  was  destined  to  play  in 


guerriere  et  de  la  conquete  affermie, 
puis  y  developper,  y  exciter  tous 
lea  travaux  de  la  pensee  sur  une 
echelle  qu'on  n'a  pas  vue  depuis 
Louis  XIV.  C'etait  le  but  de  mes 
Prix  Decennaux  qu'on  m'a  gates  par 
de  petites  intrigues  d'id-eologues,  et 
de  couronnements  ridicules,  comme 
celui  du  catechisme  de  Saint- 
Lambert." 

1  A  full  account  of  these  authors, 
their  induence  and  their  aims,  will 
be  found  in  F.  Picavet,  '  Les  Ideo- 
logues, Essai  sur  1'histoire  des  ide'es 
et  des  theories  scientifiques,  philo- 
sophiques,  religieuees,  &c.,  en  France 
depuis  1789,'  Paris,  1891. 

Thibaudeau,  '  Le  Consulat  et 
1'Empire,'  gives  many  details  re- 
garding Napoleon's  connection  with 
science,  with  literature,  and  with 
the  growing  industries  of  France. 
Among  the  latter  see  especially 


the  great  efforts  made  to  supersede 
colonial  and  foreign  goods  by  home 
productions.  Prizes  and  encourage- 
ments of  all  sorts  were  given  ; 
technical  schools  and  colleges  were 
established  ;  exhibitions  were  pro- 
moted. Sheep  were  imported  from 
Spain,  sugar  was  made  from  raisins 
and  beetroot,  saltpetre  and  soda  by 
chemical  processes,  the  garance  or 
madder  root  and  the  kerrnes  were  to 
take  the  place  of  cochcnille  ;  the  pas- 
tel the  place  of  the  imported  indigo. 
That  an  enormous  impetus  was 
thus  given  to  chemistry  cannot  be 
denied.  (See  Thibaudeau,  passim, 
and  especially  vol.  v.  p.  248,  &c.) 
See  also  Cuvier's  'Rapport,'  &c., 
for  an  account  of  applications  of 
science,  especially  chemistry,  pp. 
376-386,  and  Delambre,  '  Rapport,' 
&c.,  pp.  326-362. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN    FRANCE. 


153 


the  immediate  future.  This  part,  as  we  know,  it  has 
played  both  by  entirely  changing  the  external  face  of 
things,  and  by  running  out  into  endless  applications ;  and 
we  have  seen  the  importance  of  that  statistical  spirit  of 
numbering,  measuring,  and  registering,  by  which  alone 
a  survey  of  complicated  phenomena  is  possible.  Of  the 
statistical  method  Napoleon  himself  made  use  on  an  ex- 
tensive scale :  perhaps  he  was  the  first  among  rulers  to 
do  so.1  That  the  great  leader  of  men  has  to  recognise 
not  only  the  inductive  philosophy  of  statistics  and  aver- 
ages, but  likewise  governing  ideas  of  a  different  class, 
Napoleon  was  well  aware,  and  his  ultimate  failure  may 
be  traced  to  the  fact  that,  however  great  as  a  general 
and  as  a  calculator,  his  soul  had  no  room  for  those  high, 
religious,  and  unselfish  motives  of  which  he  himself  said 
to  Fontanes,  that  they  in  the  end  always  decide  the  fate 
of  nations.2  Yet  he  belongs  to  the  small  company  of 
great  military  figures  in  history — a  company  which  in- 
cludes Alexander  the  Great,  Caesar,  and  Peter  the  Great 


39. 

He  himself 
made  exten- 
sive use  of 
the  statisti- 
cal method. 


1  See  Delambre,  'Rapport,'  &c., 
p.  222.     "  Depuis  le  peu  de  temps 
qu'on  s'en  [i.e.,  with  statistics]  oc- 
cupe   en   France,  elle   y  a  fait  les 
plus  grands  progres,  au  moyen  de 
1'attention   particuliere  et   des   se- 
cours  que  le  Gouvernement  franoois 
donne   a   tous    les   travaux   utiles. 
Les  presets  des  departemens  ont  6t6 
invite's  a  recueillir  et  a  transmettre 
au     Ministre     de    l'inte"rieur     les 
renseignemens  les  plus   precis  sur 
toutes   les   questions   qui   sont  du 
ressort  de  la  statistique." 

2  See     '  (Euvres     litteraires    de 
Napoleon  Bonaparte,'  vol.  iii.  p.  5  ; 
Conversation  avec  Fontanes,  Saint 
Cloud,  19  Sept.  1808:  "Fontanes, 
savez-vous  ce  que  j 'admire  le  plus 
dans   le   monde  ?      C'est  1'impuis- 


sance  de  la  force  pour  organiser 
quelque  chose.  II  n'y  a  que  deux 
puissances  dans  le  monde  :  le  sabre 
et  1'esprit.  J'en  tends  par  1'esprit 
les  institutions  civiles  et  religieuses. 
A  la  longue,  le  sabre  est  tou jours 
battu  par  1'esprit."  Also  vol.  iv. 
p.  423 :  "  Les  vraies  conquetes,  les 
seules  qui  ne  donnent  aucun  re- 
gret, sont  ceux  que  Ton  fait  sur 
1'ignorance.  L'occupation  la  plus 
honorable  comme  la  plus  utile  pour 
les  nations,  c'est  de  contribuer  a 
1'extension  des  idees  humaines.  La 
vraie  puissance  de  la  Republique 
fran^aise  doit  consister  desormais 
a  ne  pas  permettre  qu'il  exiete  une 
seule  ide'e  nouvelle,  qui  ne  lui  ap- 
partienne." 


154  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

—who  have  succeeded  in  permanently  inscribing  their 

names  in  the  annals  of  science  beside  those  of  its  true 

and  great  representatives.     Some  of  the  glory  of  Laplace 

40.        and  Cuvier  falls  upon  him.     Except  for  this  Napoleon  has 

His  scienti- 

mahlrderi-  scarcety  a  place  in  the  history  of  thought.  In  it  those 
who  were  Napoleon's  servants  are  rulers  and  lawgivers ; 
it  is  they  who  enlighten  our  century.  They  were  the  first 
great  exponents  of  the  scientific  spirit,  nursed  under  the 
influence  of  the  academic  system.  This  was  peculiarly 
a  product  of  the  French  mind  and  culture.  It  is  well 
to  recall  in  the  words  of  Cuvier  what  the  scientific  spirit 
is.  At  the  end  of  the  report  which  he  presented  in  the 
year  1808  he  says : l  "  These  are  the  principal  physical 
discoveries  which  have  lighted  up  our  period,  and  which 
open  the  century  of  Napoleon.  What  hopes  do  they  not 
raise !  how  much  does  not  the  general  spirit  signify, 
which  has  brought  them  about,  and  which  promises  so 
much  more  for  the  future !  All  those  hypotheses,  all 
those  suppositions,  more  or  less  ingenious,  which  had 
still  so  much  sway  in  the  first  half  of  the  last  century, 
are  now  discarded  by  true  men  of  science :  they  do  not 
even  procure  for  their  authors  a  passing  renown.  Experi- 
ments alone,  experiments  that  are  precise,  made  with 
weights,  measures,  and  calculation,  by  comparison  of  all 
substances  employed  and  all  substances  obtained :  this 
to-day  is  the  only  legitimate  way  of  reasoning  and 
demonstration.  Thus,  though  the  natural  sciences  escape 
the  application  of  the  calculus,  they  glory  in  being  subject 
to  the  mathematical  spirit,  and  by  the  wise  course  which 
they  have  invariably  adopted,  they  do  not  expose  them- 

1  'Rapport,'  &c.,  p.  389. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    FRANCE.  155 

selves  to  the  risk  of  taking  a  backward  step ;  all  their 
propositions  are  established  with  certainty,  and  become 
so  many  solid  foundations  for  that  which  remains  to  be 
built." l 

Xor  can  we  look  upon  the  great  prominence  which       «. 

f~,  -,.,  .  .  Deserved 

Cuvier  gives  to  irench  names  in  the  course  or  his  survey  prominen 

J    given  to 

as  unjust  or  partial.  He  was  well  aware  of  the  contribu-  ^mecshb 
tions  of  other  nations :  no  one  has  spoken  in  more  gen-  Cuvier- 
erous  and  correct  terms  of  Priestley  and  Cavendish,  of 
Banks  and  Rumford,  of  Pallas,  Werner,  and  Humboldt. 
We  must  admit  the  correctness  of  the  remark,  "  that 
even  in  those  departments  where  chance  has  willed  that 
Frenchmen  should  not  make  the  principal  discoveries, 
the  manner  in  which  they  have  received,  examined,  and 
developed  them,  and  followed  them  out  into  all  their 
consequences,  places  their  names  next  to  those  of  the 
real  inventors,  and  gives  them  in  many  ways  the  right 
to  share  in  the  honour."  2 

In  the  first  decades  of  this  century  the  home  of  the 
scientific  spirit  was  France :  for  though  not  born  there, 
it  was  nevertheless  there  nursed  into  full  growth  and 
vigour.  But  it  soon  set  out  on  its  wanderings  through 

1  Compare  also  the  "Reflexions  j  technology  and  agriculture,  as  un- 

sur  la  marche  actuelle  des  Sci-  equalled  organisations  for  higher 

ences,"  being  the  introduction  to  instruction,  he  draws  attention  to 

the  '  Eloges  historiques,'  vol.  i.  p.  the  absence  of  equally  efficient  ele- 

1,  &c.  mentary  schools  and  to  the  neglect 

-  'Rapport,'  p.  391.  It  is  also  of  those  provincial  institutions 

remarkable  how  clearly  Cuvier  here  which  before  that  age  had  already 


announces  the  defects  which  the 
teaching  of  science  was  still  labour- 
ing under.  Whilst  he  rightly 
praises  the  great  Paris  institutions, 
the  medical  schools,  the  mathe- 
matical, physical,  and  polytechnic 
establishments,  the  new  schools  of 


done  so  much  to  disseminate  know- 
ledge and  learning.  At  the  end  of 
our  century  both  France  and  Great 
Britain  have  still  only  very  partially 
supplied  the  wants  which  Cuvier  so 
clearly  defines  in  the  beginning. 


156  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

other  lands  and  nations.  At  the  end  of  our  century — 
nay,  even  during  the  whole  of  the  second  half — we  find 
this  spirit  naturalised  in  Italy,  in  Germany,  in  England, 
in  the  north  and  east  of  Europe.  There  is  now  no  science 
which  can  be  named  pre-eminently  after  one  nation.  All 
nations  have  contributed  their  share  to  the  cosmopolitan 
power  and  influence  which  science  possesses.  They  have 
enlarged  and  deepened  the  scientific  spirit  and  widened 
its  career.  Thus  far  it  has  been  the  growth  of  the 
scientific  spirit  which  has  occupied  us ;  we  must  now 
proceed  to  study  its  diffusion,  and  learn  to  recognise  the 
peculiar  features  which  Germany  and  England  have  on 
their  part  contributed.  In  doing  so,  we  must  turn  away 
for  a  moment  from  the  academic  system  with  which  we 
have  been  specially  occupied. 


157 


CHAPTER   II. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT  IN   GERMANY. 


"No  Augustan  epoch  flowered, 
No  Lorenzo  favours  showered 

Ever  German  Art  upon  ; 
She  was  not  by  glory  nourished 
And  her  blossom  never  flourished 

In  the  rays  of  Royal  sun." 1 


Perhaps  with  more  correctness  Schiller  might,  early  in 
the  century,  have  applied  these  lines  to  German  science 
than  to  German  art.  If  art  and  poetry  were  only  slightly 
indebted  to  princely  protection,  German  science  was  still 
less  so.2  Leibniz's  scientific  labours  languished  while  he 


1  Schiller,  "  Die  deutsche  Muse." 

2  Astronomy  was  the  only  science 
that   enjoyed  some   little  princely 
favour.      William    IV.,    surnamed 
"  the   Wise,"    son    of    Philip    the 
Magnanimous  of  Hesse  and  himself 
Elector,  was  an  astronomer  of  some 
note,   and    stood    in    intimate   re- 
lations with  Mercator,  Tycho,  and 
other    astronomers.      In    1561    he 
built    himself    an    observatory    at 
Cassel  and  appointed  Rothmann  to 
be  his  "  Mathematicus."    Frederick 
II.    of    Denmark    gave    Tycho    a 
magnificent      observatory,      called 
"  Uranienburg,"  where  he  laboured 


from  1576  to  1597,  but  which  was 
subsequently  destroyed.  Tycho 
was  then  employed  by  the  Emperor 
Rudolf  II.,  and  inaugurated  the 
observatory  in  Prague  (1599-1601)  ; 
he  made  Kepler  his  assistant,  and 
enabled  the  latter  by  the  use  of  his 
observations  to  find  and  prove  his 
three  celebrated  laws  ("  Astronomia 
nova,"  Prague,  1609  ;  "Harmonices 
mundi,"  Linz,  1619;  "Tabula) 
Rudolphinse,"  1627).  Full  details 
will  be  found  in  Rudolf  Wolf, 
'  Geschichte  der  Astronomic,'  Mu'u- 
chen,  1877,  p.  266,  &c. 


158 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


i. 

Foundation 
of  German 
universities. 


occupied  the  position  of  historiographer  and  diplomatist 
at  the  Court  of  Brunswick,1  and  Tobias  Mayer's  valuable 
observations  were  only  published  with  the  aid  of  English 
money.2  But  if  the  German  vprinces  did  little  or  nothing 
directly  for  the  development  of  science,  they  indirectly 


1  Leibniz  (1646-1716)  entered, 
1676,  the  service  of  John  Frederick, 
Duke  of  Hanover,  as  librarian  and 
councillor.  The  Duke  died  1679, 
and  Ernest  Augustus,  who  in  1692 
was  made  Elector  of  Hanover,  suc- 
ceeded him.  Leibuiz'js  time  was 
taken  up  with  diplomatic  and  legal 
researches  and  negotiations  refer- 
ring to  the  position  of  the  House 
of  Hanover,  and  the  reunion  of  the 
Protestant  and  Roman  Catholic 
Churches  ;  latterly  with  genealogi- 
cal and  antiquarian  studies  refer- 
ring to  the  history  of  the  House  of 
Brunswick.  He  wrote  the  '  Annales 
imperii  occidentis  Brunsvicenses,' 
beginning  with  the  year  768,  the 
date  of  the  accession  of  Charles  the 
Great,  from  whom  Leibniz  proved 
that  the  House  of  Brunswick  de- 
scended through  the  Italian  House 
of  Este.  He  carried  the  history 
down  to  the  year  1005,  closing  a 
few  days  before  his  death  with  the 
words  "quos  ex  tenebris  eruendos 
aliorum  diligentiae  relinquo. "  The 
work  was  not  printed  till  1843, 
when  G.  H.  Pertz,  the  first  editor 
of  the  celebrated  '  Monumenta 
German  ite'  founded  by  the  great 
Stein,  published  it  with  an  elabor- 
ate preface.  Of  the  annoyances  to 
which  Leibniz  was  subjected  in  the 
course  of  his  studies,  see  an  account 
in  the  correspondence  with  the 
Minister  von  Bernstorff  (1705-16), 
published  by  Doebner,  Hanover, 
1882,  introduction.  See  also  Guh- 
rauer,  'Leibnitz,  eine  Biographic,' 
2  vols.,  2nd  ed.,  Breslau,  1846. 
Considering  the  greatne—  : 
Leibniz  in  so  many  different 
directions,  his  motto  is  note- 


worthy :  "  Didici  in  mathematicis 
ingenio,  in  natura  experiment  is,  in 
legibus  divinis  humanisque  auctori- 
tate,  in  historia  testimoniis  uiten- 
dum  esse." 

-  Tobias  Mayer  (1723-62),  born 
at  Marbach,  the  birthplace  of 
Schiller,  from  1751  Professor  of 
Economics  and  Mathematics  at 
Gottingen.  To  use  the  words  of 
Karsten  Niebuhr,  ' '  Though  he 
had  never  seen  a  big  ship,  he 
taught  the  English  how  to  deter- 
mine the  longitude  on  the  open 
sea."  He  competed  for  the  great 
prize  of  £20,000  offered  in  1713  by 
the  Board  of  Longitude  for  a  method 
of  determining  the  longitude  at 
sea  within  £a  accurately  ;  smaller 
prizes  being  offered  for  an  accuracy 
of  §3  and  1°.  The  prize  of  £5000, 
and  subsequently  of  £10,000.  was 
awarded  to  Harrison  in  1758  and 
1764  for  his  chronometers.  Euler 
and  Mayer  laboured  in  a  different 
direction  at  the  same  subject,  by 
publishing  lunar  tables  and  per- 
fecting the  lunar  theory.  After 
repeated  revisions.  Mayer  sent  his 
tables,  1755,  to  London,  where  they 
were  submitted  to  Bradley,  who  re- 
ported favourably  on  them.  After 
further  corrections,  and  after  also 
submitting  his  theory,  Mayer's 
widow  received,  in  1765.  £5000, 
Euler  £3000.  and  the  work  was 
published,  1770,  by  order  of  the 
Board  of  Longitude,  under  the 
title  '  Tabula?  motuum  solis  et 
luu;e  novaj  et  corrects,  auctore 
Tob.  Mayer :  Quibus  accedit 
methodus  longitudinum  promota 
eodem  auctore.' 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 


159 


furthered  her  cause  most  powerfully  by  founding  that 
great  institution  of  culture,  which  more  than  anything 
else  is  characteristic  of  the  German  mind,  in  which  it 
has  found  its  most  perfect  expression,  and  where  it  can 
be  most  exhaustively  studied — the  system  of  the  German 
universities. 

"  There  is  no  people,"  says  Mr  James  Bryce,  "  which 
has  given  so  much  thought  and  pains  to  the  development 
of  its  university  system  as  the  Germans  have  done — none 
which  has  profited  so  much  by  the  sel^ices  universities 
render — none  where  they  play  so  large  a  part  in  the 
national  life." l  If  it  is  correct  to  say  that  this  system 
owed  its  foundation  to  the  German  princes,  it  is  equally 
true  that  its  development  is  the  work  of  the  German 
people.2  It  may  be  doubtful  whether,  without  the 


2. 

Develop- 
ment of  the 
universities 
by  the 
people. 


1  See   James  Bryce's  preface  to 
the  English  translation  of  Conrad's 
valuable  book,  '  The  German  Uni- 
versities for  the  last  Fifty  Years,' 
Glasgow,   1885,  p.  xiii. 

2  A  great  deal  has  been  written 
about    the    German    universities. 
For  the  purposes  of  a  History  of 
Thought,    I    confine    myself    to    a 
reference  to  the  valuable  writings 
of    F.     Paulsen,    '  Geschichte    des 
gelehrten     Unterrichts     auf     den 
deutschen   Schulen   und   Universi- 
tiiten,'     Leipzig,     1885,    and    two 
essays     in     the    45th    volume     of 
Von     Sybel's     '  Historische     Zeit- 
schrift,'     1881.       The     succeeding 
phases   of  mediaeval  and   modern, 
of  Roman  Catholic  and  Protestant, 
of  the  thought  of  the  Church,  the 
Renaissance,  the  classical  and  the 
modern  ideals,  are  all  reflected  in 
the  foundation  and  reform  of  the 
universities    and    high    schools    of 
Germany     and     the     surrounding 
countries.       The  first  foundation*, 
in  imitation  of  the  universities  of 


Paris  and  of  Italy,  were  Prague 
1348,  Vienna  1365,  Heidelberg 
1386,  Cologne  1388,  Erfurt  1392, 
Wiirzburg  1402,  Leipsic  1409, 
Rostock  1419.  A  second  epoch — 
under  the  influence  of  the  human- 
istic studies — begins  in  the  middle 
of  the  fifteenth  century  and  adds 
eight  new  foundations — Greifswald 
1456,  Freiburg  1457,  Trier  1457, 
Basel  1459,  Ingolstadt  1472,  Tubin- 
gen 1477,  Mainz  1477,  Wittenberg 
1502,  Frankfort  on  the  Oder  1506 
(Paulsen,  'Geschichte,'  p.  14).  A 
third  epoch  begins  with  the  Refor- 
mation. The  first  Protestant  uni- 
versity is  Marburg,  founded  by 
Philip  of  Hesse,  1524.  Melanch- 
thon's  influence  is  everywhere  deci- 
sive. Tubingen  is  reconstituted  by 
Duke  Ulrich  1535  ;  Leipsic  by  Duke 
George  1539.  Basel,  after  three 
years'  suspension,  is  reopened  1532. 
Frankfort  on  the  Oder  is  reopened 
by  Joachim  of  Brandenburg  1537, 
who  also  founds  the  new  University 
of  Konigsberg  1541.  Greifswald  is 


160 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


individual  influence  of  the  former,  without  the  divided 
interests  of  the  dismembered  empire,  without  the  con- 
flicting religious  views,  the  political  and  personal  rivalry 
of  the  many  states  and  sovereigns,1  so  many  scattered 
centres  of  culture  and  learning  would  have  sprung  so 
early  into  existence;  but  it  is  not  doubtful  that  it  is 
owing  to  the  common  interests  of  the  nation,  to  the 
uniting  tie  of  the  same  language,  the  same  thought,  and 
the  same  aspirations,  that  these  scattered  centres  have 
been  in  course  «f  time  united  into  a  great  network,2  a 
vast  organisation  for  the  higher  intellectual  work  of  the 
nation  and  of  mankind.  The  German  nation  may  pride 
itself  on  possessing  at  the  present  moment  the  most 


reconstituted  on  a  Protestant  foun- 
dation 1539;  Rostock  in  1540-50; 
Heidelberg  by  the  Elector  Frederick 
II.  in  1544.  Jena  is  founded  1558 
by  John  Frederick,  Helmstadt  by 
Julius  of  Brunswick  in  1568  ;  Gies- 
sen  followed  in  1607  ;  Rinteln  in 
1621 ;  Altdorf  in  1662.  Of  the 
greatest  influence  on  German  cul- 
ture were  the  Dutch  Protestant  uni- 
versities—  Leyden  1575,  Franeker 
1585,  Utrecht  1634,  Harderwyk 
1648  ;  they  were  for  a  long  time — 
as  formerly  the  Italian  universities 
— the  goal  of  the  young  scholar's 
wanderings  (Paulsen,  p.  179). 
They — as  well  as  Geneva — held  a 
similar  position  to  the  Scotch  uni- 
versities (see  Sir  A.  Grant,  '  Story 
of  the  University  of  Edinburgh,'  vol. 
i.  pp.  21, 126, 188,  213, 229,  233, 263, 
274,  283,  297,  &c.,  vol.  ii.  p.  263). 
A  fourth  epoch  begins  with  the 
foundation  of  Halle  1694,  the  first 
really  modern  university  (Paulsen, 
p.  353).  The  spirit  of  "Bacon  and 
Leibniz,  represented  by  Thomasius, 
is  the  leading  power ;  it  is  not  by 
any  means  irreligious,  since  Francke 


(the  so-called  "pietist")  is  as  im- 
portant   a    factor    as    Thomasius. 
German   is  substituted  for  Latin. 
Other   universities  follow   the   re- 
form,     thus      Konigsberg      1735, 
Leipsic,    Wittenberg,     Helmstadt, 
Kiel,  Tubingen,  &c.     A  fifth  epoch 
— the  evolution    of    the    ideal    of 
'   science  in  the  German  sense,  Wi.i- 
j   senschaft — begins  with  the  founda- 
I   tion  of  Gottingen  in  1737.     Of  this 
]   more  in  the  text. 

1  Conrad,  loc.  cit.,  p.  2  :  "  There 
is  scarcely  a  stronger  bond  of  con- 
nection between  the  various  parts 
of  Germany  than  that  supplied  by 
the  universities,  and  in  no  other 
respect  have  the  barriers  that  sep- 
arated State  from  State  been  so  long 
broken  down.  .  .  .  The  historical 
development  cannot  be  accurately 
traced  unless  the  growing  extent  in 
which  the  south  German  universities 
are  attended  by  students  from  the 
north  be  kept  in  view." 

-  See  especially  Paulsen's  remarks 
referring  to  the  foundation  of  Got- 
tingen under  George II.  ('Geschichte 
des  gelehrten  Uuterrichts,'  p.  425). 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY. 


161 


powerful  and  best  equipped  army.  But  this  is  only  the 
creation  of  the  present  age.  With  greater  pride  it  may 
boast  of  having  trained  in  the  course  of  centuries  the 
largest  and  most  efficient  intellectual  army,  ready  at  any 
moment  to  take  up  and  carry  to  a  successful  issue  great 
scientific  undertakings  demanding  the  intense  thought 
and  labour  of  a  few  secluded  students,  or  the  combined 
efforts  of  a  large  number  of  ready  workers.  This  army 
is  scattered  through  the  length  and  breadth  of  the  land, 
and  even  beyond  its  frontiers  in  neighbouring  countries, 
wherever  universities  and  high  schools  are  situated.1  It 
is  not  a  stationary  power,  but  is  continually  on  the  move 
from  south  to  north,  from  west  to  east,  to  and  fro,  exchang- 
ing and  recruiting  its  forces,  bringing  heterogeneous  ele- 
ments into  close  contact,  spreading  everywhere  the  seed 
of  new  ideas  and  discoveries,  and  preparing  new  land 
for  still  more  extended  cultivation. 


1  The  extent  of  the  German  uni- 
versity system  cannot  be  estimated 
by  the  twenty  universities  marked 
on  the  map  attached  to  the  trans- 
lation of  Conrad's  book,  as  these 
represent  only  the  existing  univer- 
sities of  the  present  German  empire ; 
nor  yet  by  the  forty-three  univer- 
sities given  in  the  appendix,  p.  290, 
as  they  contain  only  some  of  the 
Austrian,  but  none  of  the  Swiss 
universities  ;  nor  even  by  taking  up 
Ascherson's  valuable  '  Deutscher 
Universitats-Kalender,'  which  con- 
tains the  German-speaking  univer- 
sities— thirty -four  in  number  in 
1887 — but  of  course  does  not  con- 
tain the  names  of  those  which  have 
been  suppressed.  There  are  also 
the  universities  of  Denmark,  Nor- 
way, and  Sweden,  which  have  ex- 
changed many  important  professors 
with  Germany,  and  those  of  Hol- 
land in  older,  of  Belgium  in  modern 

VOL.  I. 


times,  which  have  done  the  same 
thing.  The  Russian  universities 
also  were  largely  organised  on  Ger- 

I  man  models,  though  since  the  re- 
forms  of  1863  they  aim  at  a  more 

!  national  character.  Brandis  found- 
ed the  University  of  Athens  on 
German  lines  in  1837.  The  Russian 
University  at  Kasan,  that  ' '  ultima 
musarum  Thule,"  was  founded  in 
1804,  and  Gottingen  supplied  its 
first  professors.  From  there  and 
from  the  hardly  less  remote  Tran- 
sylvanian  town,  Maros  Vasarhely, 
there  issued  the  revolution  of  our 
fundamental  notions  in  geometry, 
and  there  is  reason  to  believe  that 
both  Lobachevsky's  and  Bolyai's 
theories  are  ultimately  connected 
with  the  speculations  of  Gauss. 
See  Prof.  A.  Vasiliev's  Address  on 
Lobache"vsky,  translated  by  Halsted, 
p.  5  sqq. 


162  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

It  is  not  my  intention  to  dwell  on  the  history  of  the 
German  universities,  on  the  gradual  growth  of  the  univer- 
sity system ;  though  every  stage  in  that  history  is  interest- 
•  ing  and  important  if  we  wish  to  understand  the  inner  work- 
ing and  usefulness  of  this  great  organisation.    Neither  do 
I  wish  to  do  more  than  just  mention,  as  an  equally  impor- 
».        tant  subject,  the  geography  of  the  German  universities  ; 

Geographi- 
cal distribu-  how  through  nearly  fifty  larger  or  smaller  towns,  in  the 

tion  of  the 

varsities'11"  course  °f  s^  centuries,  learning  and  higher  education  have 
been  spread  over  the  German-speaking  countries  of  Europe. 
These  figures  alone  suggest  the  intricacy  of  the  subject, 
the  many  springs,  the  continual  ebb  and  flow  of  the  rising 
tides  of  ideas,  the  many  courses  of  thought,  the  many 
schools  of  learning,  the  internal  conflicts,  the  unavoidable 
friction,  the  healthy  competition  and  rivalry,  the  repub- 
lican spirit,  the  impossibility  of  any  creeping  stagnation 
of  life,  the  absence  of  any  lengthened  tyranny  of  doctrine, 
of  an  oppressive  hierarchy,  or  of  idols  of  opinion  and 
belief.  I  leave  it  to  my  readers  to  indulge  in  comparisons- 
easily  suggested  by  these  different  aspects,  to  fasten  upon 
the  strong  and  upon  the  weak  points  of  this  great  system 
of  the  German  universities.1  What  I  wish  to  emphasise 

1  The  migration  of  students  as  Marburg  and  Berlin  in  Zeller ;  and 

well  as  of  eminent  professors  from  j   the  philological  criticism  of   Gott- 

one  university  to  another  is  one  of  j  fried  Herrmann  locating  itself   in- 

the    most    important    features    of  !   Zurich  in  his  celebrated  pupil  and 

German  academic  life.     Thus  we  biographer  Kochly,  and  in  Bavaria. 


find  the  imaginative  tendencies  of 
the  southern  intellect  represented 


through  Thiersch.  Jacobi  came  from 
the  lower  Rhine  to  Munich,  where 


by  Hegel  and  Schelling   in   philo-  also  Liebig  formed  a  centre  of  mod- 

sophy  transplanted  into  the  midst  ern  scientific  celebrities.     Savigny 

of    the    encyclopaedic    and    logical  in  Berlin  and  Thibaud  in  Heidel- 

sciences  of  the  North,  or  into  the   ;  berg  represent   the  historical   and 

centre  of  industrial  Switzerland  in   ;  philosophical    schools    of    German 

the   person  of  Vischer ;    the  theo-   !  jurisprudence.     Vienna  for  a  long 

logical  criticism   of   the   Tubingen  time  was  the  most  celebrated  Ger- 

school    wandering     northward     to  ;  man    training  -  school    of    practical 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY. 


163 


very  strongly  here  is  the  existence  in  the  midst  of 
European  life,  all  through  our  century,  of  this  vast  organ- 
isation for  intellectual  work,  this  great  engine  of  thought ; 
and  to  assign  to  it  one  of.  the  foremost  places  among  the 
great  agencies  with  which  we  shall  have  to  deal. 

The  beginning  of  the  present  century  found  this  great 
institution  of  university  education  in  full  swing  among  all 
the  German-speaking  nations.1  The  eighteenth  century 
brought  it  to  that  state  of  perfection  in  which  we  have 
been  accustomed  to  see  it.  In  the  course  of  that  century 
it  outgrew  its  earlier  and  more  limited  phases  of  existence, 
its  period  of  more  restricted  usefulness ;  it  emancipated 
itself  from  Court  and  personal  favouritism,  from  ecclesias- 


4. 

Full  devel- 
opment of 
the  German 


medicine  and  surgery,  whereas  Ber- 
lin concentrated  the  great  repre- 
sentatives of  the  more  recent  scien- 
tific developments.  In  the  course  of 
the  last  hundred  years  no  one  uni- 
versity has  been  allowed  to  retain 
for  any  length  of  time  the  supremacy 
in  any  single  branch.  The  light 
has  quickly  been  diffused  all  over 
the  country,  when  once  kindled  at 
one  point.  How  will  the  future 
compare  in  this  respect  ? 

1  This  is  not  quite  the  case  as 
regards  Switzerland.  The  city  of 
Basel,  which  before  the  Reformation 
was  the  seat  of  much  learning,  the 
names  of  Sebastian  Brandt,  Reuch- 
lin,  and  Erasmus  being  intimately 
connected  with  it,  had  a  university 
from  1459.  The  antagonism  to 
classical  and  polite  literature  which 
characterised  a  large  section  of  the 
Reformers  (see  Paulsen,  p.  128  sqq.) 
destroyed  many  flourishing  centres 
of  culture  ;  amongst  them  the  Uni- 
versity of  Basel,  which  was  sus- 
pended in  1529,  when  the  city 
accepted  the  Reformation,  but  re- 
opened three  years  later  in  1532. 


Geneva,  though  this  is  outside  of  the 
German-speaking  area  and  presents 
a  culture  quite  peculiar  to  itself, 
had  an  academy  from  1559,  with 
many  celebrated  professors  and 
numerous  students  of  theology  from 
all  countries  of  Europe.  Lausanne, 
Bern,  and  Zurich  had  colleges  or  high 
schools  in  the  seventeenth  century. 
But  down  to  the  nineteenth  century 
Basel  remained  the  only  university 
in  the  Continental  sense.  The 
reasons  why  Switzerland  developed 
her  university  system  so  late  are 
discussed  in  Tholuck,  'Das  akade- 
mische  Leben  des  17 ten  Jahrhun- 
derts,'  vol.  ii.  p.  314,  &c.,  where 
also  minute  information  is  given  on 
the  several  high  schools  of  Switzer- 
land. The  question  is  interesting, 
seeing  that  the  greatest  in  many 
brandies  of  science — such  as  Ber- 
noulli, Euler,  Haller,  Cuvier, 
Steiner — have  come  from  Switzer- 
land, and  that  by  reason  of  the 
names  of  Rousseau  and  Pestalozzi  it 
has  become  the  centre  of  modern 
ideas  on  education. 


164  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

tical  protection  and  influence;   it  acquired  through  the 

statutes  of  governments  or  special  foundations  larger  and 

better  secured  means  of  subsistence;   it  substituted  the 

vernacular  for  the  Latin  tongue.     The  circle  of  studies, 

though  from  early  times  professedly  all-embracing,  did 

not  become  worthily  filled  up  and  cultivated  with  equal 

5.        and  impartial  care  till  the  fourth  faculty,  the  philoso- 

sophicai      pkical  faculty,  was  properly  developed.     Theology,  law, 

isculty* 

and  medicine  conduct  their  studies  for  practical  ends 
and  purposes ;  the  two  former  especially  were  frequently 
liable  to  be  used  merely  for  the  ends  of  the  Church  or  the 
State ;  but  the  philosophical  faculty  embraces  all  those 
studies  which  aim  at  establishing  truth,  be  this  defined 
as  merely  formal  or  as  real,  as  belonging  to  method  or 
to  knowledge.  We  can  assign  a  definite  date  to  the 
firm  establishment  of  the  "  libertas  philosophandi,"  and 
the  professed  introduction  of  the  "  libertas  docendi "  in 
the  university  programme  * — namely,  the  opening  (in 
e.  1734)  of  the  University  of  Gottingen  (inaugurated  in 
sityofGot-  1737).  "  The  foundation  stone,"  says  Professor  Paulsen, 

tingen. 

"  of  the  academic  constitution  is  the  '  libertas  docendi.' 
On  this  point  Von  Miinchhausen,  whom  we  may  call  the 
real  founder  of  the  university,  and  his  two  advisers, 
Mosheim,  the  theologian  of  Helmstadt,  and  Bohmer,  the 
jurist  of  Halle,  were  agreed.  All '  inquisitiones,'  so  writes 
the  former,  choke  the  powers  '  ingeniorum,'  and  spoil  the 
beginnings  of  a  learned  society.  He  advises  above  all 
that  the  greatest  care  should  be  used  in  the  equipment 
of  the  theological  faculty.  Accordingly  Miinchhausen 
laid  his  eye  upon  men  whose  teaching  led  neither  to 

1  Paulsen,  'Geschichte  des  gelehrten  Uuterrichts,'  p.  424,  &c. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY.          165 

'  Atheismo '  nor  '  Naturalismo,'  who  neither  attack  the 
'  articulos  fundamentales  religionis  evangelicse,'  nor  in- 
troduce enthusiasm,  nor  yet  evangelical  popedom.  Like- 
wise the  jurists  received  full  freedom  for  teaching  and 
for  the  expression  of  legal  opinions,  whereas  at  Halle, 
following  the  common  rule,  the  Prussian  interest,  at 
least  in  matters  of  public  law,  was  the  measure  of 
things.  At  Gb'ttingen  the  chief  stress  was  laid  on 
the  culture  of  the  essentially  modern  sciences.  In  the 
foremost  rank  stood  the  administrative  and  historico- 
political  branches  where  Putter,  Achenbach,  Schlozer, 
Gatterer,  Heeren,  gave  to  the  university  her  world- 
wide fame ;  the  mathematical  and  scientific  branches  are 
marked  by  the  brilliant  names  of  Haller,  Lichtenberg, 
Blumenbach,  Kastner;  the  philological  branches  by 
Gesner,  Heyne,  Michaelis.  The  university  met  the  de- 
mand for  encyclopaedic  discourses.  Miinchhausen  ar- 
ranged in  1756  that  a  member  of  each  faculty  should 
deliver  a  public  course  on  the  whole  field  of  the  sciences 
taught  there ;  in  the  philosophical  faculty  Gesner  treated 
philologico-historical,  Kastner  physico-mathematical  sub- 
jects. An  'Index  Lectionum '  of  the  year  1737  shows 
nine  professorships :  1.  Politics  and  Morals.  2.  History 
of  Literature.  3.  History.  4.  Elocution  and  Poetry. 
5.  Logic  and  Metaphysics.  6.  Oriental  Languages.  7. 
Mathematics  and  Physics.  8.  Administrative  Sciences ; 
to  which  is  added,  lastly,  a  professorship  of  Philosophy 
without  special  definition."1 

It  is  evident  that,  owing  to  their  constitution,  as  well 


1  The  original  endowment  of  Got- 
tingen  was  fixed  at  16,000  thalers, 
equal  to  £2400.  This  was  more 


than    double    the    endowment    of 
Halle.     (Paulsen,  p.  425.) 


166 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


7. 

Relation  of 

'      ies 


schools. 


as  to  their  number,  the  German  universities  were  destined 
to  become  the  most  powerful  organisation  for  the  diffusion 
of  knowledge.  Further,  they  have  been  in  the  course  of 
the  present  century  more  closely  linked  with  many  hun- 
dreds of  high  schools,  and  with  the  growing  number  of 
technical  schools.1  For  both  of  these  they  had  to  train 
the  teaching  staff,  and  from  the  ranks  of  these  they 
again  largely  filled  their  own  chairs.  Thus  they  not 
only  combined  in  themselves  the  spirit  of  research  and 
the  profession  of  teaching,  but  they  infused  into  the 
widely  scattered  teaching  staff  of  many  hundreds  of 


1  The  technical  schools  in  Ger- 
many and  Switzerland  are  a  crea- 
tion of  modern  times.  We  can  dis- 
tinguish three  classes.  (1)  The 
"  Realschule. "  This  stands  in  a 
kind  of  opposition  to  the  "  Latin 
school."  The  name  (according  to 
Paulsen,  p.  483)  occurs  first  in  Halle, 
where  the  archdeacon  Semler  es- 
tablished in  1706  a  mathematical 
and  mechanical  "Realschule."  J.  J. 
Hecker  established  at  Berlin  in  1 739 
an  ' '  economico-mathematical  Real- 
schule." The  object  of  these  schools 
was  to  teach  "  Realia,"  to  introduce 
practical  rather  than  learned  infor- 
mation. A  special  development  was 
the  "  philanthropinism  "  of  Base- 
dow,  well  known  even  to  English 
readers  from  Lewes's  Life  of  Goethe 
(see  vol.  i.  p.  276,  &c.)  (2)  A 
second  class  embraces  the  ' '  Gewer- 
beschulen,"  which  may  be  rendered 
' '  Schools  of  industry."  Karl 
Schmidt  ('Geschichte  der  Pada- 
gogik,'  vol.  iv.  p.  163)  calls  Beuth 
the  founder  of  them  in  Prussia, 
1817,  and  gives  the  school  of 
Aachen  as  the  first.  They  form 
a  kind  of  bifurcation  with  the 
higher  classes  of  the  Gymnasia  (or 
learned  schools).  They  may  be 
more  specially  commercial,  agricul- 


tural, or  military.  (3)  Out  of  these 
a  third  class  —  answering  to  the 
growing  demand  for  the  practical 
application  of  the  higher  mathe- 
matical sciences  —  has  grown  up, 
named  polytechnic  schools.  The 
celebrated  Ecole  Polytechnique  of 
Paris  has  been  the  model.  The  first 
of  this  class  in  Germany  was  estab- 
lished at  Vienna  in  1816.  Then 
followed  Munich,  Hanover,  Karls- 
ruhe, Stuttgart,  Niirnberg,  Augs- 
burg, Darmstadt,  Zurich,  Aachen, 
latterly  also  Berlin  (Reichsanstalt) 
and  Brunswick  (Carolinum).  In 
many  ways  they  equal  the  univer- 
sities in  the  scientific  spirit  of  then- 
teaching.  What  is  wanting  is  the 
philosophical,  the  historical,  the 
encyclopaedic  treatment.  In  this 
respect  they  form  in  their  best 
examples  a  contrast  to  the  Gotting- 
en  programme.  To  many  serious- 
thinking  minds  they  indicate  the 
gradual  dissipation  of  the  German 
ideal  of  Wissensckaft,  the  narrowing 
down  of  Wissenschaft  to  science  in 
the  English  and  French  meaning  of 
the  word.  Their  danger  lies  in  the 
direction  of  being  contented  with 
practical  usefulness,  as  the  danger 
of  the  German  type  of  university  lay 
in  being  contented  with  erudition. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY.          167 

schools  the  same  habit — almost  absent  in  other  countries 
— of  looking  upon  private  study  and  research  as  a 
necessary  qualification  of  the  lecturer  and  teacher.  The 
educational  organisation  of  the  combined  universities  and 
higher  schools  has  thus  become  an  equally  powerful 
organisation  for  research,  and  for  increasing  knowledge. 
Wherever  the  progress  of  learning  and  science  requires 
a  large  amount  of  detailed  study  inspired  by  a  few  lead- 
ing ideas,  or  subservient  to  some  common  design  and  plan, 
the  German  universities  and  higher  schools  supply  a  well- 
trained  army  of  workers,  standing  under  the  intellectual 
generalship  of  a  few  great  leading  minds.  Thus  it  is  s. 

The  univer- 

that  no  nation  in  modern  times  has  so  many  schools  of  sity a  train- 

*    ing-school  of 

thought  and  learning  as  Germany,  and  none  can  boast  of  researck 
having  started  and  carried  through  such  a  large  number 
of  gigantic  enterprises,  requiring  the  co-operation  and  col- 
lective application  of  a  numerous  and  well-trained  staff.1 
The  university  system,  in  one  word,  not  only  teaches 
knowledge,  but  above  all  it  teaches  research.  This  is 
its  pride  and  the  foundation  of  its  fame. 


1  The  editions  of  the  ancient 
classics  brought  out  by  Tauchuitz, 
"VVeidmann,  and  Teubner  are  well 
known.  The  collections  of  the  His- 
tories of  all  countries,  begun  by 
Heeren  and  Ukert  and  continued  in 
this  century  by  the  publishing  firm 
of  Salomon  Hirzel  of  Leipsic ;  the 
4  Jahresberichte,'  started  by  Ber- 
zelius  for  chemistry,  and  now  separ- 
ately conducted  for  all  the  different 
sciences  ;  contain  summaries  of  the 
labours  of  the  whole  world  syste- 
matically arranged.  There  is  the 
geographical  establishment  of  Peter- 
maim  at  Gotha ;  not  to  speak  of 


publications    specifically    national,       men  of  science, 
euch  as  the  'Monumenta  Germanise,' 


as  other  countries  possess  similar 
undertakings.  Von  Zach  was  the 
first  to  establish  a  regular  inter- 
national organ  for  astronomical 
observations.  It  was  started  in 
1798,  and  soon  became  the  "living 
organ  of  astronomy,"  equally  ap- 
preciated by  Lalande  and  Gauss. 
This  "monthly"  was  soon  succeeded 
by  Schumacher's  "  weekly,"  the 
'  Astronomische  Nachrichten.'  See 
Wolf,  '  Geschichte  der  Astronomic,' 
p.  764,  &c.  Humboldt's  and 
Gauss's  scheme  for  a  network  of 
magnetic  observations  all  over  the 
world  was  taken  up  by  English 


168  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

It  is  a  useful  and  interesting  task  to  trace  intellectual 
developments  and  habits  to  their  external  causes.  The 
centralisation  of  the  powers  and  resources  of  a  whole 
nation  into  one  capital,  as  was  the  case  in  Eome  and  in 
Paris,  may  explain  the  brilliancy  of  their  literatures ;  the 
more  scattered  and  diffused  culture  of  Greece  and  of 
Germany  is  likewise  reflected  in  their  many  schools  of 
thought  and  learning ;  the  insular  position  of  England  has 
impressed  its  advantages  and  disadvantages  upon  her 
history,  and  has  influenced  her  mental  life.  These  influ- 
ences have  frequently  been  pointed  out  and  examined. 
The  historian  of  thought  has  another  and  more  difficult 
task  to  perform.  Habits  of  thought  and  intellectual 
qualities  never  become  the  property  of  a  large  number  of 
persons  unless  they  assume  a  definite  form  ;  through  this 
they  become  a  marketable  article  which  can  be  communi- 
cated and  transmitted,  and  in  which  those  also  can  par- 
ticipate from  whom  the  deeper  motives  and  higher  aims 
remain  hidden.  Every  school  has  its  watchword,  in  which 
its  leading  thought,  its  ideal,  is  embodied.  The  widely 
scattered  and  yet  closely  connected  community  of  intel- 
lectual workers  represented  by  the  German  university 
system,  which  covers  with  its  network  of  universities  and 
high  schools  the  German-speaking  countries  of  Europe, 
has  during  the  period  of  its  greatest  influence  developed 
its  own  special  ideal,  and  it  has  expressed  this  in  a  special 
9.  word — namelv,  the  word  Wissenschaft.  Neither  the  French 

The  ideal 

rfjp***"-     nor  the  English  application  of  the  word  science     corre- 
sponds  to   the   use  or  gives   the  meaning  of   the  word 
Wissenschaft.     This  meaning  cannot  be  defined  by  any 
1  Compare  the  notes  at  the  beginning  of  the  last  chapter,  p.  89,  &c. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY. 


169 


single  word  in  the  English  language.  Expressions  such 
as  "  student  of  science  "  or  "  science  tripos  "  have  a  mean- 
ing in  English,  but  they  would  have  none  if  translated 
into  German.  In  each  case  the  word  Wissenschaft  would 
require  a  qualification.  An  "  Academie  des  Sciences " 
could  not  according  to  German  usage  exist  separately 
beside  an  "  Acade"mie  franqaise "  or  an  "  Academie  des 
Inscriptions,"  for  it  would  include  them.1  Scientific 
treatment  in  England  means  the  exact  experimental  or 
mathematical  treatment  of  a  subject:  no  one  ever  calls 
Bentley 2  or  Gibbon 3  a  great  scientific  writer,  though  in 


1  The    two    older    academies    in 
Paris,  the  "  Academie  des  Sciences  " 
and  the  "  Academie  des  Inscriptions 
et    Belles    Lettres,"   covered    very 
nearly    the    same    ground    as    the 
modern  Berlin  "  Academie  der  Wis- 
senschaften    und    Kiinste,"    which 
is    divided    into    two    classes,    the 
' '  mathematisch  -  naturwissenschaf t- 
liche"  and  the  "philosophisch-his- 
torische    Classe,"    the    two    sides 
being  equally  comprised  under  the 
term     Wissenschaften.      A    similar 
division  exists   in   the  learned  so- 
cieties of  Vienna,  Leipsic,  Munich, 
and  Gottingen. 

2  Richard   Bentley   (1662-1742), 
popularly  known  in  England  mainly 
through    his    Boyle    Lectures,    his 
controversy  about  the  Epistles  of 
Phalaris,  and  his  thirty  years'  feud 
as  Master  of  Trinity  College,  Cam- 
bridge, with  the  dons  of  his  col- 
lege,  but  hardly   known    "as   the 
first,  perhaps  the  only,  Englishman 
who  can  be  ranked  with  the  great 
heroes  of  classical  learning"  (Mark 
Pattison,  'Ency.  Brit.'),  was  from 
the  first  recognised   as  a  consum- 
mate genius  by  the  scholars  of  Ger- 
many, by  Grscvius  and  Spanheim, 
who    welcomed    him  •  as    "novum 
et    lucidum    Britannise    sidus,"    as 
"  splendidissimum     Britannire    lu- 


men." The  many  beginnings  which 
he  had  laid  for  subsequent  critical 
research  among  the  ancient  classical 
authors  were  taken  up  abroad  by 
men  like  Heyne,  Reiz,  F.  A.  Wolf, 
Gottfried  Hermann,  and  Friedrich 
Ritschl,  in  whose  hands  they  have 
developed  into  a  special  school  of 
philology,  counting  probably  over 
a  hundred  representatives,  many  of 
whom  have  openly  avowed  their  in- 
debtedness to  Bentley.  (See  Kochly, 
'  Gottfried  Hermann,'  Heidelberg, 
1874,  pp.  115  sqq.,  142,  189.  Rib- 
beck,  'Friedr.  Wilh.  Ritschl,'  2 
vols.,  Leipzig,  1879  and  1881,  vol. 
i.  p.  229 ;  vol.  ii.  pp.  Ill,  176,  &c., 
418,  429.) 

3  Gibbon  (1737-94)  gave  a  new 
impetus  to  the  study  of  the  history 
of  Roman  law  through  the  cele- 
brated 44th  chapter  of  his  '  Decline 
and  Fall  of  the  Roman  Empire.' 
It  was  translated  by  Professor 
Hugo  of  Gottingen  and  Professor 
Warnkonig  of  Liege,  and  has  been 
used  as  the  text-book  on  Civil  Law 
in  some  of  the  foreign  universities. 
See  Smith's  edition  of  Gibbon's 
History  with  the  Notes  of  Milman 
and  Guizot,  chap,  xliv.,  note. 
Herder,  Savigny,  and  Niebuhr 
stand  all  under  the  immediate  in- 
fluence of  Gibbon,  and  Lessing  saw 


170 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


10. 

Has  been 


Germany  each  stands  at  the  head,  and  forms  the  begin- 
ning, of  a  definite  scientific  movement.  The  distinction 
between  scientific  and  philosophical  thought  which  I  have 
explained  in  the  Introduction  would  be  unintelligible  if 
science  were  translated  simply  by  Wissenschaft;  the  word 
Wissenschaft  is  not  opposed  to,  but  embraces,  the  word 
philosophy :  Fichte,  whose  whole  doctrine  was,  according 
to  French  and  English  ideas,  almost  the  reverse  of  scien- 
tific, uses  the  word  Wissenschaftslehre  to  denote  and  char- 
acterise his  system.1  In  fact  the  German  word  for  science 
has  a  much  wider  meaning  than  science  has  in  French  or 
English;  it  applies  alike  to  all  the  studies  which  are 
cultivated  under  the  roof  of  "  alma  mater " ;  it  is  an 
idea  specially  evolved  out  of  the  German  university 
system,  where  theology,  jurisprudence,  medicine,  and 
the  special  philosophical  studies  are  all  held  to  be 
treated  "scientifically,"  and  to  form  together  the  universal, 
all-embracing  edifice  of  human  knowledge.2  Such  an 

in  him  kindred  tendencies,  though 
in  a  different  direction  (see  Watten- 
bach,  '  Zum  Andenken  Lessing's,' 
p.  23). 

1  Fichte  (1762-1814)  begins  his 
first  philosophical  work,  published 
in  1794,  with  the  words,  "Philo- 
sophy is  a  science,"  and  he  then 
proceeds  to  give  to  his  philosophy 
the  term  Wissenschaftslehre,  or  gen- 
eral doctrine  or  theory  of  science. 
A  further  definition  which  he  gives 
is  as  follows :  "A  science  has  a 
systematic  form ;  all  propositions 
in  it  hang  together  in  one  single 
fundamental  proposition,  and  are 
united  by  it  into  a  whole."  It  is 
evident  that  whoever  approached 
Fichte's  writings  with  the  ideal  of 
science,  as  it  was  established  by 
the  labours  of  Lavoisier  and  the 
great  French  academicians,  would 


not  accept  these  first  sentences  of 
Fichte's  book.  He  would  admit 
that  the  sciences  as  cultivated  by 
the  great  Frenchmen  had  a  unity 
of  method,  the  exact  method,  the 
method  of  observation,  measure- 
ment, and  calculation,  but  not 
necessarily  a  unity  of  system,  or 
a  highest  all-embracing  proposition. 
It  is  evident  that  science  means 
to  Fichte  something  more  than  it 
meant  to  the  Academic  des  Sciences  : 
it  meant  Wissenschaft,  not  merely 
methodical,  but  systematic,  unified 
knowledge. 

2  It  would  be  an  interesting  task 
to  trace  in  German  literature  from 
the  time  of  Leibniz  the  gradual 
evolution  of  the  idea  of  Wissen- 
schaft. to  see  how  the  word  has 
grown  in  pregnancy  and  signifi- 
cance till  it  became  firmly  estab- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    GERMANY. 


171 


idea,  the  use  of  such  a  term,  could  only  be  born  and 
developed  where  the  different  faculties,  the  various 
branches  of  knowledge,  lived  habitually,  for  many  ages, 
under  the  same  roof,  coming  into  continual  contact,  and 
learning  to  regard  each  other  as  members  of  one  family, 
as  integral  parts  of  one  whole.  The  German  university 


lished  as  denoting  a  moral  as  much 
as  an  intellectual  ideal,  which  it  was 
the  duty  of  the  German  university 
to  uphold  and  to  realise.  Such  an 
investigation  would  have  to  show 
how  the  encyclopaedic  view  is  repre- 
sented by  Leibniz,  how  Winckel  mann 
applied  the  term  to  the  studies 
of  antiquity,  how  Lessing  taught 
method  and  clearness,  how  Herder 
widened  and  deepened  the  view,  ex- 
tending it  to  the  elemental  forces 
as  well  as  to  the  finished  forms  of 
human  culture,  how  it  was  finally 
raised  as  the  standard  of  German 
university  teaching  by  F.  A.  Wolf 
and  W.  von  Humboldt,  finding  an 
eloquent  exposition  in  Fichte's  lec- 
tures on  the  "  Nature  of  the 
Scholar"  (' Vorlesungen  iiber  das 
Wesen  des  Gelehrten,'  Erlangen, 
1805),  and  a  practical  realisation 
in  the  foundation  of  the  University 
of  Berlin  in  1809,  during  the  period 
of  Germany's  greatest  degradation. 
The  following  words  of  Fichte 
have  reverberated  in  the  soul  of 
many  a  German  scholar  to  whom 
Fichte's  philosophy  was  unknown 
or  distasteful,  and  this  same  spirit 
has  leavened  and  united  studies 
which  stand  apparently  in  no  con- 
nection with  each  other.  "The 
scholar "  (and  specifically  the 
teacher  of  scholars)  "shows  his 
respect  for  science  [  Wissenschaft] 
as  such  and  because  it  is  science, 
for  science  generally  as  one  and 
the  same  divine  Idea  in  all  the 
various  branches  and  forms  in 
which  it  appears."  Of  one  who 
may  be  seduced  into  overestimat- 


ing his  own  branch,  Fichte  says : 
"It  becomes  evident  that  he  has 
never  conceived  science  as  One, 
that  he  has  not  comprehended  his 
own  branch  as  coming  out  of  this 
One,  that  he  thus  does  not  himself 
love  his  branch  as  science  but  only  as 
a  trade ;  this  love  of  a  trade  may 
otherwise  be  quite  laudable,  but  in 
science  it  excludes  at  once  from  the 
name  of  a  scholar.  ...  In  the  aca- 
demic teacher  science  is  to  speak, 
not  the  teacher  himself,"  he  is  to 
speak  to  "his  hearers  not  as  his 
hearers  but  as  future  servants  of 
science,"  he  is  to  represent  the  dig- 
nity of  science  to  coming  genera- 
tions (Fichte,  Werke,  vol.  vi.  p. 
436,  &c.)  I  have  myself  heard 
expressions  similiar  to  these  from 
the  mouth  of  one  who  represented 
what  we  should  now  consider  the 
very  opposite  phase  of  nineteenth- 
century  thought,  from  one  of  the 
earliest  representatives  in  Germany 
of  exact  research,  Wilhelm  Weber 
of  Gottingen.  Driven  into  a  corner 
by  the  questionings  of  devoted 
friends  as  to  his  own  discoveries 
and  contributions,  which  he  was 
modestly  fond  of  tracing  to  Gauss, 
and  unable  to  deny  his  own  part, 
he  would  warmly  exclaim,  "But 
is  it  not  possible  that  science 
could  do  something  herself  ?"  Pro- 
fessor Adamson  has  pointed  out 
('Fichte,'  in  "Philos.  Classics,"  p. 
79)  how  the  fundamental  idea  in 
these  writings  of  Fichte  has  been 
made  familiar  to  English  readers 
through  the  teaching  of  England's 
greatest  modern  moralist,  Carlyle. 


172 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


system  has  the  merit  of  having  elaborated  the  widest  con- 
ception of  science,  of  having  fixed  the  highest  and  most 
general  scientific  standards.  Opposed  to  science  is  that 
which  is  unscientific,  dilettante,  popular;  that  which  is 
not  a  vocation,  but  a  handicraft ;  that  which  grows  and 
lives  outside  of  the  great  university  system,  including  in 
this  the  innumerable  learned  schools  which  form  its  base, 
and  the  academy  which  forms  its  summit. 
11.  What  France  and  England  have  elaborated  and  termed 

and  England  Science,  is  called  in  Germany  Exact  Science;    but  it  is 

"Science" 

"  opposed  to  the  German  ideal  of  science  to  hold  that  the 
exact  method  is  the  only  method  which  deserves  to  be 
called  scientific.1 


1  This  is  perhaps  not  quite  cor- 
rect. No  doubt  the  term  "  exact 
Sciences  "  is  used  frequently  during 
the  last  half  -  century  to  denote 
the  mathematical  and  experimen- 
tal sciences ;  very  much  in  the 
same  sense  as  we  see  them  de- 
fined by  Cuvier  in  the  beginning 
of  the  century,  and  described  as 
the  ground  covered  by  the  labours 
of  the  "Academic  des  Sciences." 
There  exists,  however,  in  Germany 
another  school  of  thought,  very 
influential  throughout  this  cen  - 
tury,  and  one  that  has  exerted 
a  very  wide  and  wholesome  influ- 
ence, which  stands  in  no  connec- 
tion whatever  with  the  mathema- 
tical sciences,  though  it  applies  the 
word  "  exact "  to  its  methods  and  re- 
searches. This  is  the  school  which 
maintains  that  the  real  introduc- 
tion to  the  study  of  antiquity  lies 
in  a  knowledge  of  the  ancient,  pre- 
eminently the  classical,  languages, 
as  exact  and  precise  as  any  mathe- 
matical knowledge  could  be,  and  sees 
in  an  acquisition  of  such  precise 
knowledge  the  training  necessary 
for  success  in  philological  and  his- 


torical research,  just  as  famili- 
arity with  mathematical  formula? 
and  measuring  instruments  has  long 
been  considered  quite  indispensable 
training  to  success  in  the  natural 
sciences.  Of  this  view  Gottfried 
Hermann  may  be  considered  as 
a  somewhat  one-sided,  Friedrich 
Ritschl  as  a  more  profound  and 
far-seeing,  but  equally  energetic 
representative.  It  is  Ritschl  who 
was  the  most  influential.  Without 
at  present  entering  into  the  con- 
troversies which  existed  between 
what  were  termed  the  ' '  Sprach- 
philologen"  and  the  "Sach-philo- 
logen,"  I  desire  here  to  refer  to 
the  fact  that  such  very  different  re- 
presentatives of  thought  as  Fichte, 
Weber,  and  Ritschl,  than  whom  no 
men  could  be  more  dissimilar  in 
cast  of  mind,  all  find  their  ideal 
expressed  in  the  word  Wissenschaft. 
I  have  quoted  Fichte,  the  specu- 
lative generaliser,  and  Weber,  the 
exact  mathematical  physicist.  I 
will  add  what  Ritschl,  the  critical 
philologist,  says.  He  trusted,  as 
his  biographer  reports,  "in  the 
indestructible  magnetic  force  of 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY.          173 

Before  the  methods  of  exact  science  were  introduced 
into  Germany  under  English  and  French  influences,  the 
Germans  possessed  many  scientific  methods.  There  was 
the  science  of  philosophical  criticism,  established  by 
Kant ;  the  science  of  historical  criticism,  of  Biblical 
criticism ;  the  science  of  philology :  all  these  professed 
to  have  methods  as  definite,  aims  as  lofty,  and  a  style 
as  pure,  as  the  exact  sciences  brought  with  them. 

At  present  a  tendency  of  thought  may  exist  in  Ger- 
many, akin  to  the  positive  philosophy  in  France  and 
England,  which  aims  at  introducing  the  methods  of  the 
natural  sciences  so  as  to  cover  the  whole  ground  of  re- 
search, and  to  allow  of  no  other  methods.  Should  it 
succeed,  it  will  destroy  the  essential  features  of  the 
German  university  system,  and  with  it  the  ideal  of 
Wissenschaft  as  it  has  existed  in  all  the  leading  minds 
of  Germany  during  the  last  hundred  years. 

I  intend  to  come  back  to  this  subject  later  on,  and 
to  define  more  clearly  what  the  German  ideal  of  science 
—what  Wissenschaft — is.  That  which  we  are  occupied 
with  at  present  is  the  diffusion  of  the  scientific  spirit,  in 
the  narrower  sense,  as  it  was  firmly  established  in  France 
through  the  great  mathematicians  and  scientists  at  the 


the  studies  of  classical  antiquity"; 
he  maintained  that  philology,  as 
science,  not  the  barren  training  of 
a  pedagogic  seminary,  is  the  only 
right  thing  for  future  masters. 
"  The  good  teacher  must,  even  for 
teaching  purposes,  have  and  know, 
both  in  quantity  and  quality,  more 
than  he  requires  for  immediate 
progress  ;  the  portion  he  requires 
for  immediate  communication,  for 
practical  teaching  purposes,  must 
be  delivered  out  of  the  fulness  and 


the  depth  of  knowledge  ;  it  must, 
even  in  its  circumscribed  nature, 
contain  the  germs  of  further  mental 
development.  Such  depth,  such 
fructifying  power,  comes  only  from 
science"  (Wissenschaft).  See  Rib- 
beck,  '  Leben  Ritschl's,'  vol.  ii.  p. 
277.  And  as  every  mode  of  thought, 
if  clearly  felt  and  active,  finds  its 
expression  in  language,  so  Ritschl 
was  fond  of  characterising  his  scien- 
tific method  by  the  word  aicpipeia.. 


174 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


12. 

Reception 
of  Exact 
Science  in 
Germany. 


beginning  of  this  century,  as  it  is  summed  up  in  their 
works  and  in  the  Memoirs  of  the  Institute.  What 
reception  did  it  find  in  Germany  ?  How  has  it  thriven 
under  the  German  university  system  ?  These  are  the 
questions  which  interest  us  at  present. 

The  general  recognition  of  the  purely  scientific  studies 
conducted  on  a  large  scale  by  the  French  Academy  of 
Science,  as  an  integral  portion  of  the  German  university 
syllabus,  belongs  to  the  beginning  of  the  present  century. 
During  the  first  forty  years  of  the  century  complaints 
were  continually  heard  that  some  of  the  most  important 
sciences  were  not  worthily  represented.1  The  eighteenth 


1  One  of  the  latest  instances  of 
such  complaint  is  to  be  found  in 
J.  Liebig's  paper  "  On  the  state  of 
Chemistry  in  Austria"  ('Annalen 
der  Pharmacie,'  1838,  voL  xxv.  p. 
339).  This  was  followed  by  the 
highly  interesting  pamphlet  '  On 
the  state  of  Chemistry  in  Prussia' 
(Braunschweig,  1840).  According 
to  the  eminent  author,  chemistry 
was  the  science  which  was  the  latest 
to  attain  a  worthy  domicile  and  an 
independent  footing  in  the  great 
universities  of  Germany.  Mathe- 
matical physics  had  a  centre  at 
Konigsberg,  physiology  had  been 
established  as  an  independent  sci- 
ence at  Berlin  through  the  appoint- 
ment of  Johannes  Miiller  in  1833, 
chemistry  was  still  only  taught  in 
Prussia  in  connection  with  other 
branches  of  science,  with  medicine, 
with  technology,  with  mineralogy. 
There  were  no  chemical  laboratories 
to  be  found  in  Prussia.  Men  like 
Rose,  Rammelsberg,  Mitscherlich, 
received  none  or  only  the  scantiest 
support  in  their  practical  courses  of 
chemistry.  It  is  interesting  to  note 
how  Liebig,  whilst  pointing  to  the 
enormous  importance  which  chem- 
istry possesses  from  an  economic  i 


and  political  point  of  view  by  reason 
of  its  working  great  changes  and 
revolutions,  industrial  and  other, 
insists  on  the  necessity  of  teach- 
ing chemistry  scientifically,  and  not 
with  an  immediate  practical  bias. 
In  this  respect  he  is  as  much  a 
representative  of  the  scientific 
spirit  in  the  wider  sense  as  the 
great  men  mentioned  in  the  note 
to  p.  171.  The  following  passage 
(p.  39)  may  still  be  read  with  in- 
terest and  profit :  "  I  have  found 
among  all  who  frequent  this  labora- 
tory [Giesseu]  for  technical  pur- 
poses a  prominent  inclination  to 
occupy  themselves  with  applied 
chemistry.  They  usually  follow 
hesitatingly  and  with  some  suspi- 
cion my  advice  to  leave  alone  all 
this  time-absorbing  drudgery,  and 
simply  to  become  acquainted  with 
the  necessary  ways  and  means  of 
solving  purely  scientific  questions. 
By  following  this  advice  their  minds 
learn  easily  and  quickly  how  to  find 
the  best  means ;  they  themselves 
adapt  them  to  circumstances  and 
modify  them ;  all  operations,  all 
analyses,  which  serve  to  ascertain 
a  certain  state,  which  must  be 
made  in  order  to  find  the  conditions 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY. 


175 


century  produced  in  Germany  men  of  great  scientific  im- 
portance ;  but  their  position  was  irregular  and  uncertain , 
and  they  undoubtedly  do  not  wholly  or  exclusively  belong 
to  the  history  of  the  university  system.  Leibniz,  Euler,, 
Haller,  Werner,  Markgraf,  Tobias  Mayer,  Lambert,  and 
Humboldt  are  all  intimately  connected  with  the  growth  of 
modern  science :  their  position  and  sphere  of  action  were 
in  each  case  different.1  Leibniz  was  a  courtier,  Euler  an 


for  the  solution  of  the  problem, 
have  a  definite 'sense  ;  each  of  them 
possesses  a  certain  charm  which 
dispels  fatigue,  and  if  the  question 
is  really  answered,  then  they  know 
the  ways  and  means  of  attaining 
similar  ends.  I  know  many  who 
are  now  at  the  head  of  soda-,  vitriol-, 
sugar-factories,  of  colour-works  and 
other  establishments.  Without  ever 
having  had  anything  to  dowith  them 
beforehand,  they  were  in  the  first 
half-hour  acquainted  with  the  pro- 
cesses, the  second  already  brought 
a  number  of  appropriate  improve- 
ments, &c. ,  &c."  Similarly  Helm- 
holtz  in  1862  ('Reden,'  vol.  i.  p. 
142):  "He  who  in  the  cultivation 
of  the  sciences  aims  at  immediate 
practical  usefulness,  may  be  pretty 
sure  that  he  will  miss  his  aim. 
Science  [Wittenachafi]  can  aspire 
only  to  a  perfect  knowledge  and 
a  complete  understanding  of  the 
sway  of  physical  and  mental  forces. 
The  individual  worker  must  find 
his  reward  in  the  joy  over  new 
discoveries,  as  new  victories  of 
mind  over  matter,  in  the  sesthe- 
tical  beauty  which  an  orderly  dis- 
play of  knowledge  affords,  &c.,  &c." 
How  little  do  our  modern  colleges 
of  science  correspond  with  this  view 
of  Wissenschaft ! 

1  On  Leibniz  (1646-1716),  see  p. 
158;  Werner  (1750-1817),  p.  118; 
and  Tobias  Mayer  (1723-62),  p. 
158.  A.  von  Humboldt  (1769-1859) 
is  well  known  to  English  readers. 


Leonhard  Euler  (1707-83),  a  native 
of  Basel,  passed  the  greater  part  of 
his  life  at  St  Petersburg  as  a  mem- 
ber of  the  Academy,  a  portion  of 
it  (1741-66)  as  an  Academician 
at  Berlin.  He  has  been  termed 
the  father  of  pure  mathematics,, 
inasmuch  as  he  freed  mathemati- 
cal analysis  from  geometrical  con- 
ceptions, established  the  notion  of 
function  or  mathematical  depend- 
ence, and  did  much  to  make  the- 
theory  of  numbers  an  independent 
branch  of  science.  His  memoirs, 
are  said  to  number  nearly  a  thou- 
sand ;  his  works,  if  all  printed,, 
would  fill  60  to  80  quartos  (see 
Hankel,  '  Die  Entwicklung  der 
Mathematik,'  Tubingen,  1884,  p. 
12).  Andreas  Sigismund  Markgraf 
(1709-82)  was  born  and  lived  at 
Berlin,  a  member  of  the  Academy.  > 
On  his  various  chemical  researches- 
see  Kopp,  '  Geschichte  der  Chemie,' 
vol.  i.  p.  208.  Albrecht  von  Haller 
(1708-77)  was  a  native  of  Bern. 
He  was,  next  to  Leibniz,  perhaps 
the  most  encyclopaedic  mind  of' 
modern  times,  equally  celebrated 
as  botanist,  physiologist,  and  poet. 
He  has  been  termed  the  father  of 
physiology.  Brought  up  under  the 
celebrated  Boerhaave,  he  accepted 
a  chair  at  the  newly  founded  Uni- 
versity of  Gottingen  in  1736,  and 
taught  there  for  seventeen  years 
anatomy,  botany,  medicine,  and 
surgery. 


176  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

academician,  Werner  the  head  of  a  great  mining  school, 
Humboldt  a  traveller,  Markgraf  a  private  gentleman. 
Haller,  indeed,  shone  as  a  great  light  in  the  University 
of  Gottingen,  where  he  did  more  than  any  other  to  place 
scientific  studies  on  a  level  with  classical  ones,  and  to 
create  for  them  a  permanent  abode  within  the  pale  of 
•"  alma  mater."  He  founded  in  1751,  in  close  connection 
with  the  university,  the  Gottingen  Society,  which  from 
1753  published  the  celebrated  '  Gottinger  Gelehrte  An- 
zeigen.'1  Tobias  Mayer  and  Lambert2  can  hardly  be 
said  to  have  got  much  help  either  from  the  university, 
to  which  the  former  belonged,  or  from  the  Academy,  of 
which  the  latter  was  a  member ;  their  celebrity  rests  on 
works  produced  by  private  and  unaided  effort.  Hum- 
boldt also  depended  upon  his  personal  means  and  upon 
"his  connection  with  the  Paris  Academy,  and  only  attained 
late  in  life,  and  in  the  course  of  the  present  century,  his 
•eminent  position  as  the  head  and  patron  of  German 
science.  Von  Zach  and  Olbers,  who  together  with  Tobias 
Mayer  and  Lambert  raised  German  astronomy  during  the 
eighteenth  century  to  the  level  of  English  and  French 
science,  stood  outside  the  university  system.  Von  Zach 
was  indebted  to  personal  connections,  and  ultimately 
to  Duke  Ernest  II.  of  Gotha,  for  the  position  which 


1  The   'Gottinger   Gelehrte  An- 
zeigen'  had  existed  since  1739. 

2  Job.  Heinrich  Lambert  (1728- 
77),  a  very  extraordinary  man,  was 
a   native   of    Miihlhausen,    Alsace, 
which   then   belonged   to   Switzer- 
land.    He  was  received  as  a  mem- 
ber  of   the    Berlin   Academy,   and 
associated    there   with    Euler    and 
Lagrange.    He  is  celebrated  through 


to  the  orbits  of  comets,  employed 
by  Olbers  in  his  method  for  calcu- 
lating them  (Weimar,  1797,  re- 
published  by  Encke,  1847),  and  his 
prophetic  prediction  of  the  proper 
motion  of  the  sun  (in  his  Cosmolo- 
gical  Letters,  1761).  This  motion 
was  actually  calculated  by  Sir  Wil- 
liam Herschel  in  his  paper  "  On  the 
proper  Motion  of  the  Sun  and  Solar 


his 'Photometry '(1760)  and 'Pyro-  >   System"  (' Philos.  Trans.,'  1783). 
tnetry '  (1779),his  equation  referring 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 


177 


he  held  as  a  kind  of  corresponding  centre  of  European 
astronomy,  and  as  the  leader  of  a  large  school  of  German 
astronomers  of  this  century.1  Olbers  was  a  practising 
physician  at  Bremen,2  where  Be  followed  astronomical 
studies  as  a  recreation,  making  himself  eminent  by  great 
services  to  science,  among  them  by  his  method  of  calcu- 
lating the  orbit  of  a  comet :  as  the  greatest  of  his  services 
he  counted  the  fact  of  having  discovered,  trained,  and 
appreciated  the  rising  genius  of  Bessel.3 


1  Franz  Xaver  von  Zach  (1754- 
1832)  was  a  native  of  Pesth.     After 
having  served  in  the  Austrian  artil- 
lery, and  taken  to  astronomy  as  a 
favourite  study,  he  spent  some  time 
in  Paris  and  London,  and  became 
acquainted  with  Lalande,  Laplace, 
Herschel,  Maskelyne,  Ramsden,  and 
others.     He  was  engaged  by  Dnke 
Ernest   II.    of    Gotha   in   1786    to 
erect  an  observatory  on  the   See- 
berg  near  Gotha.     This  was  com- 
pleted in  1791.     Here  he  trained  a 
number   of    younger   astronomers, 
and  was  the  first  to  establish  and 
maintain  a  periodical  specially  de- 
voted to  astronomy.     It  was  first 
(1798)    published    under  the   title 
'  Geographische  Ephemeriden,'  then 
(1800-13)  as   'Monatliche   Corres- 
pondenz  zur  Beforderung  der  Erd- 
und  Himmelskunde.'     Lalande  and 
Gauss   both   testified   to   the   use- 
fulness of  this  international  pub- 
lication,    without     which     Piazzi's 
discovery  (see  p.  182,  note  1)  would 
probably    have     been     lost.       See 
Wolf,    '  Gesch.  d.    Astronomic,'    p. 
764. 

2  Heinr.  Wilh.  Mat.  Olbers  (1758- 
1840)  was  born  near  Bremen.     He 
followed   astronomy   as    a   private 
study.      He   is   mainly  known  by 
his  rediscovery  of  the  first  of  the 
smaller  planets  (see  p.  182,  note  1), 
by  his  theory,   once  generally  ac- 
cepted, of  the  origin  of  the  smaller 

VOL.  I. 


planets  through  the  disruption  of  a 
primitive  large  planet,  and  by  his 
'  Abhandlung  iiber  die  leichteste 
und  bequemste  Methode  die  Bahn 
eines  Cometen  aus  einigen  Beo- 
bachtungen  zu  berechnen'  (1797). 
In  this  work,  by  using  Lambert's 
equation,  he  succeeded  in  perfecting 
the  methods  of  Newton  and  his  suc- 
cessors so  as  actually  to  calculate 
the  elements  of  several  comets. 
This  method  is  still  in  general  use 
(see  Wolf,  loc.  cit.,  p.  519). 

3  Friedr.  Wilh.  Bessel  (1784-1846) 
attracted  the  attention  of  Olbers  by 
his  mathematical  abilities  whilst  em- 
ployed as  clerk  in  a  shipping  office 
at  Bremen.  If  Tobias  Mayer's 
lunar  tables  were  remunerated  and 
published  with  English  money, 
Germany  repaid  the  debt  by  the 
industry  of  Bessel,  who  calculated 
and  reduced  the  observations  made 
by  Bradley  (1692-1762,  Astronomer 
Royal  from  1742)  at  Greenwich 
during  the  years  1750  to  1761. 
They  had  been  neglected  and  re- 
mained unpublished  till  1798,  when 
Olbers  induced  Bessel  to  make 
them  useful  to  science.  This  he 
did  by  calculating  from  them  some 
of  the  most  important  and  funda- 
mental data  of  astronomy.  After 
many  years  of  labour  he  brought  out 
his  '  Fundamenta  Astronomic  pro 
A.  1755  deducta  ex  observation- 
ibus  viri  incomparabilis  James 

M 


178 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


is. 

Science  not 
yet  domi- 
ciled at  the 
German  uni- 
versities 
during  the 
eighteenth 
century. 


The  general  impression  we  receive  from  a  perusal  of 
the  histories  of  science  and  learning  in  Germany  at  the 
close  of  the  eighteenth  century  is,  that  the  university 
system  had,  so  far  as  philosophical  and  classical  studies 
were  concerned,  attained  almost  to  the  eminence  which 
it  has  held  during  this  century,  but  that  it  had  not — with 
the  exception  perhaps  of  Gottingen — received  into  its  pale 
the  modern  spirit  of  exact  research,  such  as  it  had  been 
developed  by  the  great  French  Academicians.  Eminent 
students  of  science  lived  outside  of  the  universities,  belong- 
ing wholly  or  largely  to  the  international  Eepublic  which 
had  its  centre  in  Paris,  exerting  little  influence  on  higher 
German  education  through  the  universities,  and  hardly 
any  on  German  literature,  which  had  meanwhile  ripened 
into  the  age  of  Classicism.  This  scattered  condition  of 
German  science  gave  it  on  the  one  side  a  character 
which  was  foreign  to  the  general  tendencies  of  German 
thought,  since  this  had  come  under  the  excessive  in- 
fluence of  the  speculative  spirit  without  that  whole- 
some check  which  exact  research  has  always  exerted.1 


Bradley  in  specula  astronomies 
Grenoviaensi  per  A.  1750-62  insti- 
tutis '  (1818).  By  his  determina- 
tion (1838-40)  of  the  parallax  of  the 
star  61  Cygni  he  made  the  first  ac- 
curate calculation  of  the  distance  of 
a  fixed  star,  •which  he  computed  at 
12  billion  astronomical  miles. 

1  It  was  the  age  of  the  Natur- 
phttosophie,  which,  through  the  in- 
fluence of  Schelling  in  the  south 
and  Hegel  in  the  north  of  Ger- 
many, filled  the  chairs  in  the  uni- 
versities, and  penetrated  into  the 
learned  societies.  This  philoso- 
phy of  nature  had  the  effect  of 
frequently  replacing  induction  by 
speculation,  the  patient  work  of 


the  calculator,  the  observer,  the 
experimenter,  and  the  dissector  by 
general  theories,  such  as,  applied 
to  literary,  historical,  and  poetical 
subjects,  had  acquired  a  certain 
importance,  and  a  semblance  of 
veracity  and  usefulness.  In  France 
the  whole  spirit  of  the  Academy  of 
Sciences  opposed  this  form  of  learn- 
ing. Cuvier  denounced  it  or  re- 
garded it  with  suspicion,  in  Eng- 
land it  remained  unknown,  and  in 
Germany  itself  individual  great 
minds  opposed  it,  or  did  their 
work  outside  of  its  influence. 
Such  were  notably  A.  von  Hum- 
boldt  and  Gauss.  Younger  men, 
such  as  Liebig  and  Joh.  Miiller, 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY. 


179 


On  the  other  side,  we  find  in  the  wide  domain  of  gen- 
eral literature  valuable  beginnings  and  foreshadowings 
of  later  scientific  thought,  as  in  Georg  Forster l  and  in 


came  temporarily  under  its  influ- 
ence. As  regards  its  harmful 
effect  on  the  natural  and  medical 
sciences,  the  popular  addresses  of 
Helmholtz  and  Du  Bois-Reymond 
may  be  consulted.  Its  philoso- 
phical value  will  frequently  oc- 
cupy us  in  later  chapters  of  this 
work.  Its  period  can  be  approxi- 
mately fixed  by  the  publication  in 
1797  of  Schelling's  '  Ideen  zu  einer 
Philosophic  der  Natur.'  The  death 
of  Hegel  in  1831,  and  Humboldt's 
Berlin  lectures  during  the  years 
1827  and  1828,  may  be  considered 
as  marking  approximately  the  end 
of  the  generation  which  came 
under  the  one-sided  influence  of 
the  Naturphilosophie.  We  shall 
have  ample  occasion  later  on  to 
notice  how  many  valuable  leading 
ideas  connected  with  this  phase 
of  thought  were  temporarily  aban- 
doned and  have  since  come  promi- 
nently before  the  scientific  world. 
The  year  1830  marked  the  victory 
of  Cuvier's  ideas  over  those  of  his 
great  contemporary  Geoffrey  St- 
Hilaire  in  the  French  Academy, 
and  with  it  the  temporary  defeat 
of  the  valuable  suggestions  con- 
tained in  the  writings  of  Lamarck 
and  Goethe. 

1  Georg  Forster  (1753-94)  was  one 
of  those  unique  men  in  the  history 
of  literature  and  science  who  com- 
bine the  artistic  with  the  scientific 
spirit,  promoting  equally  the  inter- 
ests of  poetry  and  of  exact  know- 
ledge by  a  loving  study  of  Nature, 
leading  to  new  views  of  art  as  well 
as  to  deeper  conceptions  in  science. 
He  may  be  classed  with  White  of 
Selborne  and  other  naturalists  of 
England  among  the  small  number 
of  those  who  quietly  and  unostenta- 
tiously prepared  the  healthier  forms 


of  Naturalism  which  permeate  the 
poetical  and  scientific  thought  of  our 
century,  culminating  in  the  great 
names  of  Wordsworth  and  Goethe, 
of  Humboldt  and  Darwin,  of  Wal- 
lace and  Haeckel.  His  life  presented 
many  interesting  and  some  un- 
happy episodes ;  it  introduces  us 
into  the  political  aspirations  of 
the  early  French  Revolution,  to 
which  he  sacrificed  himself.  It 
has  been  written  by  Moleschott,  the 
naturalist,  by  Heinrich  Kb'nig,  the 
novelist  ('G.  Forster  in  Haus  und 
Welt,'  Leipzig,  1858,  2  vols.),  by 
Klein  ('Georg  Forster  in  Mainz'). 
Fr.  Schlegel  ('  Charakteristiken  und 
Kritiken,'  vol.  i.),  Gervinus  (Intro- 
duction to  the  7th  vol.  of  '  Georg 
Forster's  Werke'),  and  Hettner 
('  Literatur  des  18ten  Jahrhunderts,' 
vol.  iii.)  have  written  appreciative 
essays  on  him.  A.  von  Humboldt 
calls  him  his  master  ('Kosmos,' 
vol.  i.  p.  345),  and  Herder  (Pre- 
face to  Georg  Forster's  translation 
of  'Sakuntala')  prophesies  his  last- 
ing fame  against  the  opinion  of 
his  less  appreciative  contempor- 
aries. He  has  a  place  in  the  class- 
ical literature  both  of  England  and 
Germany  through  his  beautiful  de- 
scription of  Captain  Cook's  second 
voyage  round  the  world  —  his 
father,  Joh.  Reinhold  Forster,  hav- 
ing been  selected  as  the  naturalist 
on  that  voyage  (London,  1777,  2 
vols.  4to),  German  edition,  1779. 
Richard  Garnett  has  said  of  him  : 
"His  account  of  Cook's  voyage  is 
almost  the  first  example  of  the 
glowing  yet  faithful  description  of 
natural  phenomena  which  has  since 
made  a  knowledge  of  them  the 
common  property  of  the  educated 
world.  ...  As  an  author  he  stands 
very  high ;  he  is  almost  the  first 


180 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


Goethe ; l  but  they  could  hardly  be  encouraged  and  de- 
veloped sufficiently  without  that  strict  training  which  is 
acquired  through  the  routine  of  the  class-room,  or  under 
the  eye  of  a  recognised  authority. 
14.  The  want  of  academic  union  and  organisation,  and  the 

Scientific 

periodicals,  scattered  situation  of  the  many  small  centres  of  learning 
and  culture  in  Germany,  led,  however,  to  the  early  de- 
velopment of  those  scientific  periodicals  which  form  such 
a  characteristic  feature  in  German  literature.  They  were 
the  medium  for  the  exchange  of  ideas,  and  the  collecting- 
ground  for  researches,  in  an  age  when  exact  science  was 
not  systematically  taught  at  the  Universities,  and  when 
such  researches  otherwise  would  have  run  the  risk  of 
being  lost  in  obscurity  or  oblivion. 

At    the    end    of    the    eighteenth    century    Germany, 


and  almost  the  best  of  that  valu- 
able class  of  writers  who  have  made 
science  and  art  familiar  by  repre- 
senting them  in  their  essential 
spirit,  unencumbered  with  techni- 
cal details"  ('Ency.  Brit.,'  vol.  ix. 
p.  419).  Forster  lived  in  the  period 
of  transition  from  the  thought  of 
the  eighteenth  century  to  that  of 
the  nineteenth,  and  a  study  of  his 
Life,  Works,  and  Correspondence  is 
a  very  good  introduction  to  nearly 
all  the  great  problems  which  then, 
especially  on  the  Continent,  trou- 
bled the  minds  of  the  greatest  men. 
If  he  may  be  accused  of  want  of 
patriotism,  he  is  certainly  to  be 
admired  for  his  freedom  from  na- 
tional narrow-mindedness. 

1  It  has  taken  nearly  a  century 
before  the  real  value  of  Goethe's 
scientific  ideas  has  been  correctly 
gauged.  His  non  -  academic  sur- 
roundings, his  unscientific  style,  his 
antagonism  to  Newton,  his  mission 
as  a  poet — supposed  in  those  days 
to  be  less  realistic  than  we  have 


since  become  accustomed  to  con- 
sider it — all  these  circumstances 
contributed  to  the  result  that 
Goethe's  scientific  writings  were 
not  taken  au  sdrieux  by  the  natural- 
ists of  his  age.  Then  came  a  period 
when  men  of  science  began  to  sift 
the  wheat  from  the  chaff ;  but  even 
they  have  only  tardily  recognised 
that,  more  than  in  special  dis- 
coveries or  suggestions,  his  great- 
ness lies  in  that  general  conception 
of  Nature  which  was  so  foreign  to 
his  age,  and  which  nevertheless  is 
becoming  more  and  more  familiar 
and  necessary  to  ours.  See  espe- 
cially Helmholtz's  valuable  essays 
on  Goethe  as  naturalist  from  the 
years  1853  and  1892  ('Vortrage,' 
vol.  i. ,  and  address  delivered  at  the 
meeting  of  the  Goethe  Society  at 
Weimar,  1892),  and  the  remark- 
able progress  of  his  own  views  on 
this  subject  contained  therein.  We 
shall  have  ample  opportunity  of  re- 
verting to  this  subject. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 


181 


though  not  by  its  universities,  was  already  an  import- 
ant power  in  the  Eepublic  of  exact  science  which 
then  had  its  centre  in  Paris.  Just  at  the  beginning 
of  the  nineteenth  century  two  events  happened  which 
foreboded  for  the  highest  branches  of  the  mathematical 
sciences  a  revival  of  the  glory  which  in  this  depart- 
ment Kepler  and  Leibniz  had  already  given  to  their 
country.  These  two  events  are  both  coupled  with  the 
name  of  Carl  Friedrich  Gauss.  They  added  greatly  15. 

J  J    Gauss's 


to  the  reputation  of  the  University  of  Gottingen,  with 
which  this  remarkable  man  was  connected  for  half  a  searches- 
century.1  The  first  was  the  publication  of  the  '  Dis- 
quisitiones  Arithmetics  '  in  Latin  in  1801  —  a  work  by 
which  Gauss  placed  himself  on  a  level  with  the  great 
mathematicians,  Euler,  Lagrange,  and  Legendre.2  The 


1  Carl  Friedrich  Gauss  (1777- 
1855),  a  native  of  Brunswick,  called 
by  Laplace  the  first  mathematician 
of  Europe,  may  be  considered  as 
the  first  and  foremost  representa- 
tive of  the  modern  mathematical 
school,  of  which  we  shall  have  to 
treat  later  on.  Unlike  most  of 
the  great  mathematicians  of  the 
Continent,  he  was  self-taught,  and 
followed  in  his  earliest  works  quite 
independent  lines  of  thought ;  re- 
sembling in  this  the  great  isolated 
thinkers  of  Britain  whose  ideas  take 
a  generation  or  more  to  penetrate 
into  the  text-books  of  the  school. 
Gauss  had  the  highest  opinion  of 
the  dignity  of  pure  science,  and  it 
almost  appears  as  if,  among  the 
moderns,  only  Newton  had  come 
up  to  his  ideal.  For  him  alone 
he  reserves  the  adjective  "  sum- 
mus,"  and  he  adopts  his  synthetic 
and  classical  methods  of  exposition, 
removing,  as  has  been  said,  the 
scaffoldings  by  the  aid  of  which  he 
had  erected  his  monumental  works. 


Gauss  trained  few  mathematicians  ; 
but  among  the  few  who  penetrated 
the  secret  of  his  ideas  are  such 
original  thinkers  as  the  Hungarian 
Bolyai  (1775-1856),  the  geometers 
Mobius  (1790-1868)  and  Von  Staudt 
(1798-1867),  who  all  mark  quite 
independent  lines  of  research.  On 
Gauss  see  Sartorius,  '  Gauss  zum 
Gedachtniss,'  Leipzig,  1856  ;  Han- 
selmann,  '  K.  F.  Gauss,'  Leipzig, 
1878;  E.  Schering,  'C.  F.  Gauss,' 
Gottingen,  1887. 

2  It  appears  that  Gauss,  to  whom 
the  arithmetical  discoveries  of  Fer- 
mat  and  the  proofs  of  Euler,  La- 
grange,  and  Legendre  remained  for 
a  long  time  unknown  (see  his  Works, 
edited  by  Schering,  vol.  i.  p.  6  ; 
vol.  ii.  p.  444),  had  independently, 
in  his  eighteenth  year,  as  a  student 
at  Gottingen,  already  arrived  at  a 
great  number  of  propositions  refer- 
ring to  the  properties  of  numbers, 
and  had  then  also  found  methods 
of  geometrically  constructing  the 
regular  polygon  of  seventeen  sides. 


182 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


second  was  the  invention  of  a  new  and  shorter  method 
of  calculating  the  orbit  of  a  planet  from  a  limited  number 
of  contiguous  observations.1  This  method  was  conimuni- 


The  latter  was  the  first  addition 
made  after  2000  years  to  the 
knowledge  of  this  matter  possess- 
ed by  the  ancients.  (See  '  Disquis. 
Arithm.,'  sec.  365:  "  Magnopere 
sane  est  mirandum,  quod,  quum 
jam  Euclidis  temporibus  circuli 
divisibilitas  geometrica  in  tres  et 
quinque  partes  nota  fuerit,  nihil 
his  inventis  intervallo  2000  anno- 
rum  adjectum  sit,"  &c.  ;  and  his 
manuscript  note  to  this  passage, 
given  by  Schering,  vol.  i.  p.  176  : 
"  Girculum  in  17  partes  divisibilem 
esse  geometrice,  deteximus  1796, 
Mart.  30.")  It  is  probably  owing 
to  the  independent  manner  in  which 
Gauss  approached  the  subject  that 
he  early  found  the  necessity  of 
treating  subjects  of  higher  arith- 
metic (i.e.,  of  the  theory  of  num- 
bers or  "  discrete  magnitudes  "  as 
distinguished  from  algebra,  which 
is  the  theory  of  "continuous  mag- 
nitudes") by  an  independent  me- 
thod, for  which  he  invented  a 
language  and  an  algorithm.  He 
thus  raised  this  part  of  mathe- 
matics into  an  independent  science, 
on  which  the  '  Disquisitiones  Arith- 
metics'  is  the  first  elaborate  and 
systematic  treatise.  Legendre's 
'Traite  des  nombres'  (1799)  is  a 
complete  thesaurus  of  all  that  was 
at  that  time  known  and  of  what 
was  added  by  him,  but  it  does  not 
attempt  to  establish  the  science  on 
a  new  basis. 

1  On  the  1st  January  1801 
Piazzi  at  Palermo  had  found  a 
movable  star  of  8th  magnitude, 
RA.  57°  47',  ND.  16°  8',  which  he 
announced  to  Bode  at  Berlin  as  a 
comet  on  the  24th  January  ;  but 
a  few  days  later  he  concluded  it 
must  be  a  planet,  and  named  it 
"  Ceres  Ferdinandea."  No  one  be- 


sides Piazzi  could  find  the  star,  but 
several  astronomers,  Piazzi  himself, 
Olbers  at  Bremen,  and  Burckhardt 
at  Paris,  tried  to  calculate  the  orbit 
from  the  observations  of  the  dis- 
coverer, which  were  contained 
within  only  9  degrees.  The  at- 
tempt to  do  so  under  the  sup- 
position of  either  a  circular  or  a 
parabolic  or  an  elliptic  orbit  failed, 
and  Olbers  expressed  the  fear  that 
with  the  circular  or  elliptic  ele- 
ments which  had  been  published  in 
Zach's  periodical,  it  might  prove 
impossible  to  find  the  star  when 
it  should  again  become  visible. 
Very  near  the  expected  time,  as 
late  as  the  beginning  of  December, 
Gauss  communicated  his  elements 
to  Von  Zach,  who  published  them 
at  once,  recommending  astronomers 
to  follow  Dr  Gauss's  figures  and 
look  6°  to  7°  more  eastward  than 
the  positions  of  Burckhardt,  Piazzi, 
and  Olbers  indicated.  And  actu- 
ally on  the  7th  December  1801 
Zach  himself,  and  on  the  1st  Janu- 
ary 1802  Olbers,  succeeded  in  find- 
ing the  star,  "like  a  grain  of  sand 
on  the  sea -shore,"  very  near  the 
positions  calculated  by  Gauss. 
These  results,  followed  soon  by 
the  discovery  of  other  planets  by 
Olbers  and  Harding,  gave  a  great 
impetus  to  the  study  of  astronomy. 
Gauss's  methods  were  published 
in  extenso  in  the  now  celebrated 
'  Theoria  motus  corporum  cceles- 
tium'  in  1809.  Two  problems  are 
herein  treated  in  a  novel  and  com- 
plete manner.  The  first  was  to 
calculate  by  a  simple  and  accurate 
method  from  the  necessary  number 
of  observations  the  orbit  of  a  planet 
or  comet  on  the  assumption  of  New- 
ton's law  of  gravitation,  but  with- 
out any  other  special  conditions. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY.          183 

cated  to  Von  Zach  in  the  course  of  the  year  1801,  and 
enabled  him  and  Olbers  to  rediscover  the  first  of  the 
small  planets,  Ceres,  which  Piazzi  had  observed  on  the 
1st  of  January  1801  at  Palermo,  and  afterwards  lost  as 
it  approached  the  region  of  the  sun's  light.  Through 
this  Gauss  placed  himself  on  a  level  with  the  great 
French  astronomers  Laplace,  Lalande,  and  others.  The 
new  professor  of  mathematics  and  director  of  the  obser- 
vatory of  Gottingen  was  admitted  into  the  august  com- 
pany of  the  Paris  academicians,  who  then  ruled,  and  since 
the  death  of  Euler  had  almost  monopolised,  the  mathe- 
matical studies  of  the  world.  Although  Gauss  thus 
introduced  the  higher  and  abstract  branches  of  exact 
science  into  the  programme  of  a  German  university, 
and  established  a  link  between  Paris  and  Germany 
in  mathematics,  as  Humboldt  had  done  shortly  before 
in  the  natural  sciences,  fully  a  quarter  of  a  century 
was  to  elapse  before  the  spirit  of  exact  research,  and  ie. 
of  the  higher  mathematics,  really  began  to  leaven  the  spirit  enters 

the  unlver- 

German  universities.     It  then  at  length  entered  the  field  ^^n  {££_ 
as  a  third  and  equally  important  agent  by  the  side  of  the  cent°uiy!e 

This   was    achieved   to   perfection,   !    most  correct  average  result  ?     This 
a   proof   of   the  usefulness  of   the   i    involves  a  question  in  probabilities. 


method  being  the  fact  that  Gauss 
succeeded  in  finishing  in  one  hour 
a  calculation  which  had  taken  Euler 
three  days,  and  had  resulted  in  his 
blindness.  The  second  problem 
arises  from  the  fact  that  the  num- 
ber of  observations  is  always  in 
excess  of  the  number  mathemati- 
cally neeeseary,  and  that,  owing  to 
the  unavoidable  inaccuracies,  dif- 
ferent sets  of  observations  give 
slightly  different  orbits.  How  are 
these  to  be  used  so  as  to  give  the 


As  early  as  1795  Gauss  was  in  pos- 
session of  the  so-called  method  of 
least  squares,  which  occurred  to  him 
so  naturally  that  he  suspected  that 
Tobias  Mayer  must  have  already 
known  about  it.  It  also  occurred 
independently  to  Legendre,  who 
was  the  first  to  publish  it,  in  1806, 
in  his  '  Nouvelles  mdthodes  pour  la 
determination  des  orbites  des  co- 
metes.  '  See  Sartorius,  '  Gauss  zum 
Gediichtniss, '  p.  41  sqq. 


184 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


philosophical  and  classical  spirit.  During  these  twenty- 
five  years  Gauss  lived  and  soared  in  solitary  height — a 
name  only  to  the  German  student,  as  Euler  had  been 
before  him.  Probably  he  was  better  known  to  the 
younger  astronomers  whom  he  trained,  and  the  elder  ones 
with  whom  he  corresponded.  But  astronomy  was  not 
then  within  the  pale  of  the  universities.  To  what  extent 
the  character  of  Gauss's  own  genius  was  the  cause  of  this 
it  is  difficult  to  say.1  He  himself  had  not  come  under 
the  influence  of  any  great  teachers  such  as  Paris  then 
possessed;  he  was  self-taught,  and  had  early  imbibed 
a  great  admiration  for  the  methods  of  Euclid,  Archimedes, 
and  Newton ;  he  wrote  in  the  classical  style  fitted  for  all 
times,  but  not  for  uninitiated  beginners.2  It  is  certain, 


1  Bjerknes,  in  his  most  interesting 
memoir  on  Abel,  refers  frequently 
to  the  awe  in  which  Gauss  was  held 
by  younger  mathematicians. 

2  In  this  Gauss  resembled  New- 
ton.   He  was  therefore,  like  Newton, 
frequently    forestalled    by    others, 
who    published    his    new    methods 
and  ideas  in  an  unfinished  and  frag- 
mentary form;  whereby  it  is  not 
suggested  that  these  simultaneous 
discoveries  or  inventions  were  not 
quite  independent.     Two  examples 
of  this  may  be  added  to  those  given 
above.     When  Gauss  published  the 
'Disquis.  Arith.'  in  1801,  he  left 
out  the  last  or  eighth  section,  which 
was  to  treat  of  the  residues  of  the 
higher    orders.      He    had    already 
nearly    completed    the    theory    of 
biquadratic    residues.     In    dealing 
with  this  subject  he  had  found  it 
necessary  to  extend  the  conception 
of  number  beyond  the  limits  then 
in  use.     If  we  confine  ourselves  to 
integers,  the  only  extension  which 
then  existed  of  the  notion  of  number 
was  in  the  use  of  negative  numbers. 


These  were  counted  on  a  straight 
line  backward,  as  positive  (or  or- 
dinary) numbers  were  counted  for- 
ward. Gauss  conceived  the  idea  of 
counting  numbers  laterally  from  the 
straight  line  which  represented  the 
ordinary — positive  and  negative — 
numbers.  He  called  numbers  which 
were  thus  located  in  the  plane 
"complex  numbers,"  as  they  had  to 
be  counted  by  the  use  of  two  units, 
the  ordinary  unit  1  and  a  new  unit 
i.  He  also  showed  that  this  new 
unit  i  stood  in  such  relations  to  the 
ordinary  unit  1  as  were  algebraically 
defined  by  the  mysterious  imagin- 
ary symbol  N/-l.  The  complete 
exposition  of  this  new  or  complex 
system  of  counting  was  not  ex- 
plained by  Gauss  till  the  year 
1831,  when  he  published  the 
'  Theoria  residuorum  biquadrati- 
corum.'  In  the  meantime  the 
geometrical  representation  of  im- 
aginary quantities  had  been  devised 
and  published  by  Argand  (1806), 
but  not  being  employed  for  such 
important  researches,  it  had  re- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY. 


185 


however,  that  the  spirit  of  exact  and  specially  mathe- 
matical research  owed  its  right  of  domicile  within  the 
universities  to  others  who  came  after  him,  and  to  cir- 
cumstances with  which  he  was  hardly  connected. 

The  man  to  whom  Germany  owes  its  first  great  school 
of  mathematicians  was  Jacobi.  He  was  self-taught  like 
Gauss ;  but  whilst  Gauss  followed  in  the  footsteps  of 
Newton  and  the  ancients,  Jacobi  followed  in  those  of 
Euler,  Lagrange,  and  Laplace.  The  style  and  methods 
of  these  mathematicians,  being  more  suited  for  didactic 
purposes  than  the  classical  style  of  Euclid,  Newton,  and 
Gauss,  was  probably  more  congenial  to  the  mind  of 
Jacobi,  who  from  his  twenty-first  year  (1825)  developed 
a  great  activity  as  an  academic  teacher.1  He  was  first 


maiued  unknown  and  unnoticed. 
See  on  the  history  of  the  subject, 
Hankel,  '  Theorie  der  complexen 
Zahlensysteme,'  1867,  pp.  71,  82. 
Gauss,  through  hiding  his  researches 
on  this  subject  so  long,  lost  the 
claim  to  the  priority  of  the  inven- 
tion, though  not  of  the  effectual 
use  of  it.  In  another  instance  he 
allowed  others  to  appropriate  the 
merit  of  cultivating  a  large  new 
field  which  had  been  familiar  to 
him  many  years  before.  It  was 
known  all  through  the  first  half  of 
the  century  that  Gauss  was  in  pos- 
session of  valuable  discoveries  in 
what  he  termed  the  "  new  transcen- 
dent functions. "  References  in  the 
'  Disquisitiones,'  §  335,  in  his  corres- 
pondence with  Schumacher,  Bessel, 
Olbers,  and  Crelle,  had  made  his 
friends  curious  to  see  the  "  amplum 
opus"  which  he  had  promised.  It 
appears,  however,  that,  independ- 
ently of  him,  Jacobi  and  Abel 
(1802-29)  following  the  investiga- 
tions of  Legendre  (whose  labours 
began  in  1786  and  culminated  in 


his  great  work  '  Traite  des  fonctions 
elliptiques,  &c.,'  1825-28,  2  vols. 
and  3  supplements),  succeeded  in 
developing  the  theory  very  much, 
on  the  same  lines  as  Gauss  had 
taken  nearly  a  generation  earlier. 
Eminent  mathematicians  who,  since- 
the  publication  of  Gauss's  posthu- 
mous papers,  have  fully  investi- 
gated the  subject,  assign  to  Jacobi 
and  Abel  the  undisputed  priority 
of  publishing,  but  to  Gauss  that  of 
discovering,  the  fundamental  pro- 
perties of  the  "  doubly  periodical " 
functions.  Full  details  will  be 
found  in  the  historical  introduction 
to  Enneper's  '  Elliptische  Func- 
tionen,'  2nd  ed.,  Halle,  1890.  See 
also  Gauss's  Werke,  vol.  iii.  p.  491- 
496  ;  Dirichlet's  Discourse  on  Jacobi 
in  Jacobi's  Werke,  vol.  i.  p.  11  ;  C. 
A.  Bjerknes,  'N.  H.  Abel,'  Paris, 
1885;  Koenigsberger,  'Zur  Ges- 
chichte  der  Theorie  der  elliptischen 
Transcendenten,'  Leipzig,  1879. 

1  Carl  Gustav  Jacob  Jacobi  (born 
at  Potsdam  1804,  died  at  Berlin 
1851)  was  the  first  great  rnathe- 


186  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

at  Berlin,  then  at  Konigsberg;  these  two  universities 
having  become  through  him  and  Bessel  the  German 
teaching  centres  of  the  higher  mathematics,  both  pure 
and  applied.  They  have  up  to  the  present  day  fully 
maintained  this  pre-eminent  position.  They  were  teach- 
ing centres  in  the  sense  defined  above — not  only  as 
regards  mathematical  knowledge  and  method,  but  like- 
wise as  regards  mathematical  research.  For  this  pur- 
pose— as  in  the  philological  sciences — the  lecture-room 
was  not  sufficient:  there  was  also  wanted  a  repository 
for  the  independent  and  original  contributions  of  the 
school.  Like  the  £cole  polytechnique  thirty  years  before 
in  Paris,  the  Berlin  school  of  mathematicians  started  with 
an  important  periodical.  This  was  known  as  Crelle's 
Journal.  Together  with  the  Memoirs  of  the  Paris  Aca- 
demy and  the  Journal  de  1'Ecole  polytechnique,  it  forms 
the  principal  repository  for  the  higher  mathematical  work 
of  the  first  half  of  the  century.1  It  was  also  through 

matical  teacher  of  Germany.  Of  they  could  hope  to  do  something 
him  Lejeune  Dirichlet  says  :  "  It  similar.  .  .  .  The  success  of  this 
was  not  his  business  to  communicate  unusual  method  was  truly  remark  - 
what  was  finished  and  what  had  able.  If  in  Germany  the  knowledge 
been  communicated  before ;  his  of  the  methods  of  analysis  is  now 
lectures  all  treated  of  subjects  spread  to  a  degree  unknown  to 
which  lay  outside  of  the  field  of  former  times,  if  numerous  mathe- 
the  text-books,  and  covered  only  maticians  extend  the  science  in 
those  parts  of  science  in  which  he  every  direction,  this  gratifying  re- 
had  himself  been  creative.  With  suit  is  principally  owing  to  Jacob!. 
Mm  this  meant  that  they  exhibited  Nearly  all  have  been  his  pupils," 
the  greatest  variety.  His  lectures  i  &c.  (Dirichlet's  Discourse  in  the 
were  not  remarkable  for  that  kind  Academy  of  Berlin,  1852,  Jacobi's 
of  clearness  which  is  character-  !  Werke,  vol.  L  p.  21.) 
istic  of  intellectual  poverty,  but  for  i  l  The  two  mathematicians  on 
a  clearness  of  a  higher  kind.  He  i  whom  A.  L.  Crelle  (1780-1855)  re- 
tried primarily  to  show  the  leading  j  lied  mainly  for  contributions  when 
ideas  which  underlay  any  theory,  !  he  started  the  '  Journal  fiir  die 
and  whilst  he  removed  everything  reine  und  angewandte  Mathematik ' 
that  had  an  artificial  appearance,  {  in  1826  were  Abel  and  Steiner. 
the  solution  of  problems  presented  For  originality  of  thought  they 
itself  so  easily  to  his  hearers  that  I  stand  quite  alone.  Both  extended 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 


187 


Jacobi,  and  still  more  through  his  contemporary  Lejeune 
Dirichlet  (born  1804  at  Diiren,  of  French  extraction, 
and  trained  in  Paris  under  Laplace,  Legendre,  Fourier, 


the  field  of  research  which  they 
cultivated  by  fundamentally  new 
ideas  of  such  breadth  that  fully 
half  a  century  was  required  be- 
fore they  were  thoroughly  appreci- 
ated by  mathematicians.  Abel 
(a  Norwegian  by  birth)  died  in 
1829  when  only  twenty -seven 
years  old,  having  during  the  four 
years  whicli  embrace  his  published 
memoirs  extended  the  limits  of 
algebra  and  laid  the  foundations 
for  a  more  comprehensive  treat- 
ment of  the  higher  or  transcendent 
functions,  or  forms  of  mathematical 
dependence.  Mathematicians  be- 
fore him  had  tried  to  solve  algebra- 
ically equations  beyond  the  fourth 
degree,  but  had  failed.  Abel  proved 
that  the  problem  as  then  conceived 
could  not  be  generally  solved.  Le- 
gendre had  through  his  unaided 
labours,  extending  over  thirty 
years,  established  the  theory  of 
elliptic  integrals  as  far  as  was 
possible  on  the  lines  then  adopted. 
Abel — and  simultaneously  Jacobi — 
treated  the  subject  from  an  entirely 
novel  point  of  view,  and  by  doing 
so  opened  out  quite  a  new  field  of 
research,  the  extent  and  importance 
•of  which  Abel  fully  recognised  when 
he  presented  to  the  French  Acad- 
emy his  memoir  of  1826,  in  which 
he  dealt  with  functions  of  which 
those  studied  by  Legendre  and 
Jacobi  were  only  special  cases. 
This  memoir,  containing  Abel's 
celebrated  theorem,  which  he  had 
already  discovered  in  1825,  and 
which  was  published  in  a  brief  ar- 
ticle in  Crelle's  Journal  in  1829,  re- 
mained unnoticed,  being,  as  Legen- 
dre explained  to  Jacobi,  almost  un- 
readable. See  Enneper,  'Elliptische 
Functionen,'  2nd  ed.,  p.  192;  Jaco- 
bi's  Werke,  vol.  i.  p.  439,  &c.  Abel 


has  been  called  the  greatest  mathe- 
matical genius  that  has  yet  existed 
(Oltrainare  in  '  La  grande  Encyclo- 
pe"die,"  art.  "Abel");  his  fellow- 
worker,  Jacob  Steiner  (1796-1863, 
a  Swiss  by  birth),  has  been  termed 
the  greatest  geometrician  of  modern 
times.  The  progress  of  analysis 
had  thrown  into  the  background 
purely  geometrical  researches,  al- 
though a  revival  of  these  had  com- 
menced in  France  with  Monge  and 
his  followers,  and  had  been  further 
promoted  by  Poncelet,  as  well 
as  simultaneously  by  Mobius  and 
Pliicker  in  Germany.  The  labours 
of  the  two  latter  remained  for  a 
long  time  unknown  and  unrecog- 
nised. Steiner,  who  was  self- 
taught,  who  disliked  the  calculus, 
and  'considered  it  a  disgrace  that 
geometry  could  not  solve  her  prob- 
lems by  purely  geometrical  methods, 
undertook  to  find  the  common  root 
and  leading  principle  which  con- 
nected all  the  theorems  and  por- 
isms  bequeathed  to  us  by  ancient 
and  modern  geometry  ;  he  brings 
order  into  the  chaos,  and  shows 
how  nature  with  a  few  elements 
and  the  greatest  economy  succeeds 
in  giving  to  figures  in  space  their 
numberless  properties.  He  not 
only  completed  that  part  of  geome- 
try which  had  been  treated  by  the 
ancients — the  geometry  of  the  line, 
the  conic  sections  or  curves  of  the 
second  order,  and  the  surfaces  in 
space  corresponding  to  them — but 
he  also  attacked  problems  which 
before  him  had  been  solved  only  by 
the  calculus,  and  even  succeeded  in 
carrying  his  methods  beyond  the 
reach  of  the  calculus  of  varia- 
tions, specially  invented  to  deal 
with  geometrical  questions.  Like 
Fermat  in  the  theory  of  numbers, 


188 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


18. 
Chemical 


Poisson,  Cauchy),  that  the  great  work  of  Gauss  on  the 
theory  of  numbers,  which  for  twenty  years  had  remained 
sealed  with  seven  seals,  was  drawn  into  current  mathe- 
matical literature,  and  became,  as  Newton's  '  Principia ' 
had  become  a  century  earlier,  an  inexhaustible  mine  of 
wealth  for  succeeding  generations. 

About  the  same  time  the  experimental  side  of  exact 
research — the  use  of  the  chemical  balance,  through  which 

established 

Lavoisier  and  his  followers  had  done  so  much  to  establish 
chemistry  on  a  firm  and  independent  basis — received  a 
great  impetus  by  the  establishment  of  the  first  chemical 
laboratories  within  the  pale  of  the  universities.1  In  this 
direction  the  greatest  influence  probably  belongs  to  the 
small  town  of  Giessen,  where  Liebig  opened  his  cele- 
brated laboratory  in  the  year  1826.  It  became  the 


in  1826 
through 


Steiner  in  geometry  left  to  his  fol- 
lowers a  large  number  of  theorems 
and  problems  without  proofs  which 
he  had  solved  by  his  methods  ;  and 
it  was  only  in  quite  recent  times 
that  the  Italian  Cremona  succeed- 
ed in  definitely  clearing  up  the 
whole  of  this  original  and  valuable 
bequest.  See  Hankel,  '  Die  Ele- 
mente  der  projectivischen  Geome- 
trie,  chapter  i.  ;  Jacob  Steiner, 
Werke,  vol.  ii.  p.  495. 

1  On  Liebig's  laboratory  see  Hof- 
mann's  Faraday  Lecture,  p.  8. 
Chemical  laboratories  existed  for 
teaching  purposes  before  Liebig's 
at  Giessen.  Kopp  ('  Geschichte  der 
Chemie,'  vol.  ii.  p.  19)  mentions  one 
at  Altorf,  which  was  founded,  1683, 
by  the  council  of  the  city  of  Niirn- 
berg  for  academic  teaching  pur- 
poses. For  the  training  of  the 
modern  school  of  chemists  no  man 
did  more  than  Berzelius,  in  whose 
laboratory  there  were  trained  Chr. 
Gmelin,  Mitscherlich,  H.  and  G. 


Rose,  Wohler,  Magnus,  Arfvedson, 
Nordenskiold,  Mosander,  and  others. 
Sir  William  Thomson  (Lord  Kelvin) 
in  '  Nature,'  vol.  xxxi.  p.  409,  men- 
tions the  beginnings  of  laboratory  - 
teaching  at  Glasgow  by  Prof. 
Thomas  Thomson  in  1828.  But 
what  was  probably  peculiar  to 
Liebig's  laboratory  was  the  syste- 
matic and  methodical  training,  on 
a  specially  devised  plan,  in  quali- 
tative, quantitative,  and  organic 
analysis,  by  which  young  persons 
were  introduced  to  a  thorough 
knowledge  of  chemical  properties 
and  manipulations.  The  guides, 
text-books,  and  tables  for  analytic 
work  of  Will,  Fresenius,  and  others 
were  elaborated  to  meet  the 
requirements  of  such  methodical 
teaching.  Almost  simultaneously 
with  Liebig  at  Giessen,  Purkinje  at 
Breslau  laid  the  foundation  for  the 
first  physiological  laboratory.  See 
Du  Bois-Reymond,  'Reden,'  vol.  ii. 
p.  367. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC.  SPIKIT   IN   GERMANY.          189 

training -school  for  the  greater  part  of  the  eminent 
chemists  outside  of  Paris,  and  the  model  for  similar 
establishments,  and  extended  its  influence  over  the 
world — into  England,  Scotland,  and  America.  It  also 
did  more  than  any  other  institution  of  that  kind  for  the 
development  of  ready  and  accurate  methods  of  analysis, 
such  as  are  now  used  in  the  remotest  regions.  But  it 
was  significant  for  German  chemistry,  and  for  the  cos-  19. 

Cosmopoli- 

mopolitan  character  of   German  science  generally,  that  tancharac- 

J  '  ter  of  Ger- 

this  brilliant  development  of  experimental  research  was  manscience. 
stimulated  from  two  independent  centres;  that  German 
chemists  as  little  as  German  mathematicians  attached 
themselves  in  a  one-sided  manner  to  the  Paris  school. 
In  mathematical  science  the  classical  style  of  Gauss, 
transmitted  from  the  ancients  through  Newton,  com- 
bined with  the  analytical  or  modern  French  style  of 
Jacobi  and  Dirichlet  to  give  to  German  research  its 
character  of  universality.  In  a  similar  manner,  when 
chemistry  again  found  a  domicile  in  Germany  and  be- 
came an  integral  portion  of  the  university  programme, 
it  had  been  trained  in  two  different  schools.  For  there 
lived  at  that  time  in  Sweden  the  eminent  authority  Ber- 
zelius,1  who  divides  with  Gay-Lussac  the  glory  of  being 


1  J.  Jacob  Berzelius  (a  Swede, 
1779-1848),  one  of  the  most  eminent 
and  industrious  of  chemists,  had  a 
great  influence  on  the  development 
of  modern  chemistry  by  the  num- 
ber as  well  as  by  the  accuracy  of  his 
experimental  determinations,  by  his 
invention  of  methods  and  apparatus 
for  analysis,  and  by  his  extensive 
proofs  of  several  of  the  most  im- 
portant theories.  The  latter  di- 
rected the  labours  and  governed  the 
opinions  of  many — especially  Ger- 


man— i  n vestigators.  1 1  was  through 
him  mainly  that  Richter's  chemi- 
cal equivalents  and  Dalton's  atomic 
theory  were  extensively  verified  and 
applied  to  all  parts  of  the  science, 
to  organic  and  mineralogical  chem- 
istry. He  also  elaborated,  in  close 
connection  with  Davy's  electrical 
discoveries,  his  celebrated  electro- 
chemical theory,  which  up  to  the 
year  1840  was  very  generally  ac- 
cepted by  chemists  ;  and  he  assisted 
through  his  repeated  expositions 


190 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


the  master  of  the  great  German  chemists  of  the  middle 
of  the  century.  Mitscherlich  at  Berlin  and  Wohler  at 
Gottingen  belonged  to  the  school  of  the  former,  whereas 
Liebig  had  the  good  fortune  to  be  introduced  through 
Humboldt  into  Gay-Lussac's  laboratory  at  Paris  as  the 
first  pupiL1 


and  criticising  in  breaking  down  the 
older  oxygen  theory  of  acids  in  fa- 
TOUT  of  Davy's  more  general  view*, 
based  upon  his  recognition  of  chlo- 
rine and  iodine  as  elementary  bodies. 
His  handbook  of  Chemistry,  as  well 
as  his  '  Jahresbericht'  (from  1820), 
probably  did  more  than  any  other 
publications  for  the  diffusion  of  ac- 
curate chemical  information. 

1  Liebig  has  himself,  in  an  auto- 
biographical memoir  published  post- 
humously, so  fully  described  the 
merits  of  the  two  schools,  and  at 
the  same  time  given  such  a  vivid 
picture  of  the  truly  scientific  spirit 
which  animated  German  universi- 
ties at  that  time,  that  I  am  tempt- 
ed to  give  here  some  extracts.  Of 
his  studies  in  Paris  he  says  :  "  What 
influenced  me  most  in  the  French 
lectures  was  their  inner  truthfulness 
and  the  careful  omission  of  all  mere 
semblance  of  explanations :  it  was 
a  complete  contrast  to  the  German 
lectures,  in  which,  through  a  pre- 
ponderance of  the  deductive  pro- 
cess, the  scientific  doctrine  had  quite 
lost  its  rigid  coherence.  ...  I  re- 
turned to  Germany  (1824),  where, 
through  the  school  of  Berzelius, 
...  a  great  reform  had  already 
begun  in  inorganic  chemistry.  .  .  . 
I  always  remember  with  pleasure 
the  twenty -eight  years  which  I 
passed  at  Giessen  :  it  was,  as  it  were, 
a  higher  providence  which  led  me 
to  the  small  university.  At  a  large 
university,  or  in  a  larger  town,  my 
powers  would  have  been  broken  up 
and  frittered  away,  and  the  attain- 
ment of  the  aim  which  I  had  in 


view  would  have  been  much  more 
difficult,  if  not  impossible ;  but  at 
Giessen  all  were  concentrated  in 
the  work,  and  this  was  a  passion- 
ate enjoyment,"  "  The  necessity  of 
an  institute  where  the  pupil  could 
instruct  himself  in  the  chemical  art, 
by  which  I  understand  familiarity 
with  chemical  operations  of  analysis 
and  adroitness  in  the  use  of  appar- 
atus, was  then  in  the  air.  and  so  it 
came  about  that  on  the  opening  of 
my  laboratory  .  .  .  pupils  came 
to  me  from  all  sides.  .  .  .  The 
greatest  difficulty  presented  itself, 
as  the  numbers  increased,  in  the 
practical  teaching  itself.  In  order 
to  teach  many  at  once,  an  ordered 
plan  was  required  and  a  progres- 
sive way  of  working,  which  had 
to  be  thought  out  and  tried.  .  .  . 
A  very  short  time  had  sufficed  for 
the  celebrated  pupils  of  the  Swedish 
master  to  give  to  mineral  analysis 
...  an  admirable  degree  of  per- 
fection. .  .  .  Physical  chemistry 
.  .  .  had  through  the  discoveries 
of  Gay-Lussac  and  Humboldt.  .  .  . 
and  of  Mitscherlich,  .  .  .  gained  a 
solid  foundation,  and  in  the  chemi- 
cal proportions  the  edifice  appeared 
to  have  received  its  coping-stone. 
.  .  .  No  organic  chemistry  .  .  .  then 
existed  ;  Thenard  and  Gay  -  Lus- 
sac,  Berzelius,  Prout,  Dobereiner, 
had  indeed  laid  the  foundation  of 
organic  analysis ;  but  even  the 
great  investigations  of  Chevreul  on 
the  fatty  bodies  received  for  many 
years  only  scant  attention.  Inor- 
ganic chemistry  still  absorbed  too 
many,  and  indeed  the  best,  forces. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 


191 


Twenty  years  after  Gauss's  great  mathematical  achieve- 
ments, two  new  discoveries  announced  to  the  scientific 
world  that  Germany  had  again  taken  a  foremost  position 
in  chemistry.  These  were  Mitscherlich's  discovery  of 
isomorphism  in  1819,1  and  Wohler's  preparation  of  an 
organic  compound  from  inorganic  materials  in  1828.2 

In  1830  Liebig  succeeded  in  finally  establishing  that 
simple  and  accurate  method  of  organic  analysis  known  organic 

analysis. 

by  his  name.     Organic  chemistry,  in  its  modern  sense, 


20. 

Liebig's 


The  direction  I  had  received  in 
Paris  was  a  different  one.  ...  I 
saw  very  soon  that  all  progress  in 
organic  chemistry  depended  on  its 
simplification.  .  .  .  The  first  years 
of  my  residence  at  Giessen  were 
almost  exclusively  devoted  to  the 
improvement  of  organic  analysis, 
and  with  the  first  successes  there 
began  at  the  small  university  an 
activity  such  as  the  world  had  not 
yet  seen.  ...  A  kindly  fate  had 
brought  together  in  Giessen  the 
most  talented  youths  from  all 
countries  of  Europe.  .  .  .  Every 
one  was  obliged  to  find  his  own 
way  for  himself.  .  .  .  We  worked 
from  dawn  to  the  fall  of  night : 
there  were  no  recreations  and 
pleasures  at  Giessen.  The  only 
complaints  were  those  of  the  at- 
tendant, who  in  the  evenings,  when 
he  had  to  clean,  could  not  get  the 
workers  to  leave  the  laboratory." 
See  '  Deutsche  Rundschau,'  <vol. 
Ixvi.  pp.  30-39. 

1  Eilhard  Mitscherlich  (1794- 
1863),  a  pupil  of  Berzelius,  dis- 
covered in  1819  that  in  compound 
bodies  which  crystallise  in  definite 
forms  certain  elements  can  be  re- 
placed by  others  in  the  proportion 
of  their  chemical  equivalence  with- 
out changing  the  form  of  crystallisa- 
tion. Such  elements  are  termed 
"  isomorphous."  Berzelius  declared 


this  to  be  the  most  important  dis- 
covery that  had  been  made  since 
the  theory  of  chemical  proportions 
had  been  established. 

-  This  synthesis  was  the  prepara- 
tion of  urea,  a  highly  organic  sub- 
stance, out  of  the  compounds  of 
cyanogen,  with  the  examination  of 
which  he  and  Liebig  were  then  oc- 
cupied. "  It  was  the  first  example 
of  the  fact  that  an  organic  sub- 
stance could,  by  chemical  methods 
alone,  be  produced  out  of  inor- 
ganic materials  ;  this  discovery  de- 
stroyed the  difference  which  was 
then  considered  to  exist  between 
organic  and  inorganic  bodies — viz., 
that  the  former  could  only  be 
formed  under  the  influence  of  vege- 
table or  animal  vital  forces,  where- 
as the  latter  could  be  artificially 
produced  "  (Kopp,  '  Geschichte  der 
Chemie,'  vol.  i.  p.  442).  It  must 
here  be  remarked  that  this  state- 
ment is  only  correct  if  the  sub- 
stances, cyanic  acid  and  ammonia, 
out  of  which  Wohler  produced  urea, 
are  considered  to  be  inorganic  ;  in- 
asmuch as  neither  of  them  had  then 
been  produced  otherwise  than  out 
of  organic  substances,  the  popular 
notion  on  Wohler's  important  dis- 
covery requires  this  correction.  See 
Kopp,  'Gesch.  der  Wissenschaften 
in  Deutschland ,'  vol.  x.  p.  546. 


192 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


may  be  said  to  date  from  these  and  other  simultaneous 
labours  of  Liebig  and  "Wohler.1  But  although  the  pure 
sciences,  mathematics,  physics,  and  chemistry,  advanced 
on  new  lines  in  the  hands  of  German  students,  and 
although  theoretical  investigations  have  always  been 
favourite  pursuits  of  theirs,  as  we  shall  have  ample 
opportunity  to  note  in  the  course  of  our  further  survey, 
the  greatest  contribution  to  the  progress  of  science,  and 
the  most  brilliant  performances  of  the  exact  spirit  of 
research  which  emanated  from  Germany  during  the  first 
half  of  this  century,  lay  in  a  different  direction.  And  it 
is  hard  to  believe  that  the  conditions  favourable  to  this 
peculiar  growth  could  have  been  found  anywhere  else 
than  in  the  German  universities.  The  many  elements  of 
thought  which  meet  on  that  ground,  the  equal  dignity 


1  The  joint  labours  of  Liebig 
(1803-73)  and  Wohler  (1800-82), 
which  have  become  of  such  im- 
portance to  science,  form  one  of 
the  most  interesting  instances  of 
scientific  co-operation  between  two 
men  pursuing  different  lines  of 
thought  and  trained  in  different 
schools.  See  the  preface  to  Hof- 
mann's  edition  of  Liebig  and  Woh- 
ler's  Correspondence.  In  Liebig's 
autobiographical  sketch,  quoted 
above,  he  thus  enlarges  on  his  re- 
lations to  Wohler:  "It  was  my 
good  fortune  that,  from  the  be- 
ginning of  my  career  at  Giessen, 
similar  inclinations  and  endeavours 
secured  me  a  friend,  with  whom, 
after  so  many  years,  I  am  still  (be- 
tween I860  and  1870)  connected 
by  ties  of  the  warmest  affection. 
Whereas  in  me  the  tendency  pre- 
dominated to  look  for  the  likenesses 
of  substances  and  their  combina- 
tions, he  possessed  an  incomparable 
talent  for  seeing  their  differences ; 


acuteness  of  observation  was  joined 
in  him  to  an  artistic  aptitude  and 
to  a  genius  for  finding  new  ways 
and  means  of  analysis  such  as  few 
men  possess.  The  perfection  of 
our  joint  researches  into  uric  acid 
and  the  oil  of  bitter  almonds  has 
been  frequently  praised  ;  this  is  his 
work.  I  cannot  sufficiently  estimate 
the  advantage  which  both  my  own 
and  our  joint  aims  derived  from  my 
union  with  Wohler ;  for  in  them 
were  combined  the  peculiarities  of 
two  schools,  and  the  good  which 
each  had,  attained  its  value  through 
co-operation.  Without  grudge  or 
jealousy  we  pursued  our  way  hand 
iu  hand ;  if  one  required  help,  the 
other  was  ready.  An  idea  can  be 
formed  of  this  mutual  relation 
when  I  mention  that  many  of  the 
smaller  productions  which  bear  our 
names  belong  to  one  alone  :  they 
were  charming  little  presents  which 
one  gave  the  other"  (p.  39). 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIKIT    IN   GERMANY. 


193 


which  there  belongs  to  pure  and  to  applied  science, 
the  continual  contest  which  exists  there  between  meta- 
physical and  exact  reasoning,  and  the  general  ebb  and 
flow  of  rival  currents  of  ideas,  all  seem  to  have  been 
necessary  to  raise  to  the  rank  of  an  exact  science  those 
researches  which  deal  with  the  phenomena  of  life  and 
consciousness  in  their  normal  and  abnormal  forms  of  ex- 
istence. In  the  hands  of  German  students  *  chemistry 
and  physics,  botany  and  zoology,  comparative  anatomy 
and  morphology,  pathology,  psychology,  and  metaphysics, 
have  laboured  from  different  and  unconnected  beginnings 
to  produce  that  central  science  which  attacks  the  great 
problem  of  organic  life,  of  individuation,  and  which  studies 
the  immediate  conditions  of  consciousness.  Physiology t 
or  to  use  its  more  comprehensive  name,  Biology,2  may  be 

furnished  for  a  long  period  the 
systematic  treatises  for  the  whole 
world  (vol.  ii.  p.  196).  Physiology 
has  therefore  with  some  right  been 
termed  a  German  science  (see 
Helmholtz,  'Vortrage,'  &c.,  vol.  i. 
pp.  339,  362  ;  Du  Bois-Reymond, 
'Reden,'  vol.  ii.  p.  265).  Com- 
pare also  what  Huxley  says, 
'  Critiques  and  Addresses,'  pp.  221, 
303.  On  the  connection  of  phy- 
siology with  all  other  sciences  see 
likewise  Helmholtz,  loc.  cit.;  Du 
Bois  -  Reymond,  vol.  ii.  p.  341  ; 
Huxley,  'Lay  Sermons,'  &c.,  p. 
75;  'Science  and  Culture,'  p.  52:: 
"  A  thorough  study  of  human  phy- 
siology is,  in  itself,  an  education 
broader  and  more  comprehensive 
than  much  that  passes  under  that 
name.  There  is  no  side  of  the  in- 
tellect which  it  does  not  call  into 
play,  no  region  of  human  know- 
ledge into  which  either  its  roots  or 
its  branches  do  not  extend,"  &c. 

2  The  word  "biology"  seems  to 
have    been    first    used    by    G.   R.. 


21. 

Biology  t 

German 


1  The  two  greatest  discoveries 
in  physiology  belong  to  England. 
These  are  Harvey's  discovery  of  the 
circulation  of  the  blood  in  the  seven- 
teenth century,  and  Charles  Bell's 
discovery  of  the  difference  of  sensory 
and  motor  nerves  in  the  early  part 
of  this  century.  The  two  men,  how- 
ever, who  have  done  most  to  estab- 
lish physiology  as  an  independent 
science,  whose  systematic  works 
have  done  most  for  the  student 
of  physiology,  are  probably  Haller 
(see  supra,  p.  176),  whose  '  Ele- 
menta'  cast  into  the  shade  all 
older  handbooks,  and  Johannes 
Muller  (1801-58),  whose  '  Hand- 
buch'  (1833-40)  was  translated 
into  French  and  English.  See  Du 
Bois-Reymond,  '  Reden,'  &c. ,  vol. 
ii.  pp.  143,  &c.,  195,  360,  who  also 
points  out  how  in  other  sciences, 
like  mathematics,  physics,  chem- 
istry, Germans  made  use  almost 
exclusively  of  translations  of  French 
and  English  text-books  and  hand- 
books, whereas  in  physiology  they 

VOL.  I. 


N. 


194  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

said  to  be  a  German  science  as  chemistry  has  been 
named  a  French  science.  I  have  already  referred  to  the 
great  Haller  in  the  last  century,  who  may  be  called  the 
father  of  physiology ;  to  Blumenbach,  the  comparative 
anatomist ;  and  to  Liebig  and  Wohler,  who  first  among 
chemists  succeeded  in  producing  an  organic  compound  by 
the  processes  of  inorganic  chemistry.  I  have  now  to  add 
two  names,  which  together  mark  a  great  revolution  in  our 
ideas  of  the  structure  of  organisms,  and  link  together 
the  two  sciences  which  had  treated  separately  of  the 
Celine  animal  and  vegetable  worlds.  About  the  year  1838 
schieiden  Mathias  Schieiden  l  propounded  his  cellular  theory  con- 

Treviranus  (1776-1837),  a  learned  j  deal   with  living   things,    whether 

physician  of  Bremen,  who  began  to  |  they  be  animals  or  whether  they 

write  his  ' Biologic oder  Philosophic  i  be  plants"  (loc.  cit.,  p.  138).     It 

der  lebenden  Natur'  in  1796  and  !  can  be  divided  into  three  branches 

to  publish  it  in  1802  (6  vols.,  1802-  — (1)  Morphology,  which  comprises 

22).      Lamarck  used  the  word  in  :  the  sciences  of  anatomy,  develop- 

his  '  Hydrogeologie,'  1801.     They,  i  ment,   and   classification  ;    (2)   the 

as  well  as  Bichat  about  the  same  science  of  the  distribution  of  living 

time,  independently  "  conceived  the  '  beings,  present  and  past;  and  (3) 

notion  of  uniting  the  sciences  which  ;  physiology,  which  deals  with   the 

deal  with  living  matter  into   one  functions    and    actions    of    living 

whole,   and  of  dealing  with  them  |  beings,  and  tries  to   "deduce  the 


as  one  discipline  "  (Huxley,  on  the 
study  of  Biology,  1876,  in  'Ameri- 
can Addresses,'  p.  136,  &c.)  The 
term,  though  of  German  origin,  has 


facts  of  moi-phology  and  of  distribu- 
tion from  the  laws  of  the  molecular 
forces  of  matter  "  (Huxley,  '  Lay 
Sermons,'  &c.,  p.  83,  1864).  To 


not  found  favour  in  that  country,  i    these   three   Huxley  adds  ('  Ency. 

and  after  having  been  used  officially  Brit.,'  art.   "Biology")  the  infant 

in  France  and  England,  makes  its  science  of  "aetiology,"  which  "has 

appearance  in  Germany  only  since  j   for  its  object  the  ascertainment  of 


the  great  works  of  the  modern 
English  school,  headed  by  Darwin, 
have  gained  so  much  influence  in 
Germany.  In  the  meantime  the 
biological  sciences  had  been  exten- 
sively represented  at  the  German 
universities  by  chairs  of  physiology, 
zoology,  botany,  &c.  According  to 
Huxley,  biology  has  been  "substi- 
tuted for  the  old  confusing  name 
of  natural  history,"  and  "denotes 
the  whole  of  the  sciences  which 


the  causes  of  the  facts  of  biology 
and  the  explanation  of  biological 
phenomena,  by  showing  that  they 
constitute  particular  cases  of  general 
physical  laws"  (p.  688). 

f  Mathias  Jacob  Schieiden  (1804- 
81),  for  some  time  Professor  of 
Botany  at  Jena,  was  a  man  of 
peculiar  ability  and  disposition, 
combining  a  philosophical  mind 
with  exact  knowledge  and  a  gen- 
eral literary  taste,  not  frequently 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY. 


195 


cerning  the  structure  and  growth  of  plants.     About  the  and 

Schwann. 

same  time  Theodor  Schwann l  extended  this  theory  to 
animal  organisms.  A  variety  of  circumstances  combined 
to  make  the  announcement  of  the  cellular  theory,  which 
will  always  be  associated  with  those  two  names,  an  epoch 
in  the  history  of  scientific,  indeed  of  general,  thought. 

The  historian  of  botany,  Julius  Sachs,  describes  the 
publication  of  Schleiden's  great  work  as  a  burst  of  day- 
light,2 and  Du  Bois-Reymond  says  :  "  In  order  to  measure 
the  magical  progress  which  it  marks,  one  must  have  wit- 
nessed the  rise  of  the  cellular  theory,  when  it  suddenly 
spread  daylight  in  the  darkness  of  the  hidden  structure 


to  be  found  among  men  of  pure 
science  in  Germany.  Opposed  to 
the  idealistic  philosophy  as  a  fol- 
lower of  Fries,  and  on  the  other  side 
to  the  dry  systematisation  of  the 
Linmcan  school,  he  was  the  man  at 
once  to  broaden  the  scientific  view 
and  to  create  a  popular  interest  in 
the  "  life  of  the  plant  "-world.  The 
titles  of  his  two  best  known  works 
are  characteristic,  '  Die  Botanik  als 
inductive  Wissenschaf t '  (1842-45), 
and  his  short-lived  periodical  (filled 
with  the  labours  of  his  equally  im- 
portant co -editor,  Nageli),  '  Zeit- 
schrift  fur  wissenschaftliche  Bo- 
tanik.' 

1  Through  the  friendship  of 
Schleiden  and  Schwann  (1810-82, 
a  pupil  of  Johannes  W  tiller  and 
professor  at  Louvain),  two  inde- 
pendent courses  of  research  and 
scientific  thought  were  brought  to- 
gether. Schleiden  placed  the  "cell" 
— a  term  used  before  him  by  Hooke, 
Malpighi,  Grew,  Wolff,  Brown,  and 
Mirbel — in  the  forefront  of  his  de- 
scription as  the  element  of  form 
and  as  the  origin  of  life,  or — as  we 
now  express  it — as  the  morphologi- 
cal and  embryological  unit,  in  the 
plant.  A  similar  series  of  great 


names,  beginning  with  Bichat  and 
leading  up  to  Johannes  Miiller, 
marks  the  studies  of  animal  tissues. 
Schwann,  struck  with  the  analogy 
of  Schleiden's  nucleated  cells  and 
similar  structures  which  he  had 
observed  in  the  notochord,  con- 
ceived and  verified  on  a  large  scale 
the  idea  ' '  that  a  common  principle 
of  development  exists  for  the  most 
different  elemental  parts  of  the 
organism,  and  that  the  formation 
of  cells  is  this  principle."  This  is 
the  beginning  of  the  cellular  theory, 
which  produced  at  once  a  recon- 
struction of  the  whole  of  "  general 
anatomy"  by  Jacob  Henle  (1809- 
85),  and  subsequently  the  "  cellu- 
lar pathology  "  of  Rudolph  Virchow. 
As  the  latter  has  himself  said,  he 
aims  at  the  establishment  of  a  gen- 
eral biological  principle,  and  thus 
the  discovery  of  Schleiden  and 
Schwann  is  characterised  as  the 
transition  from  the  "  historical "  to 
the  "  biological"  study  of  animated 
nature. 

2  See  Julius  Sachs,  '  Geschichte 
der  Botanik  vom  16  Jahrh.  bis 
I860,'  p.  203,  and  in  many  other 
passages. 


196 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


of  animals  and  plants,  where  the  rays  of  comparative  ana- 
tomy and  embryology  could  not  reach."1  This  bold  gener- 
alisation, which  had  been  prepared  by  a  long  series  of 
botanical  and  morphological  researches  in  and  out  of  Ger- 
many, met  alternately  with  applause  and  criticism ;  it  gave 
rise  to  a  long  controversy,  and  was  the  starting-point  of  a 
whole  line  of  important  discoveries.2  It  secured  for  Ger- 
many a  long  period  of  supremacy  in  physiological  science. 
This  supremacy  was  more  than  maintained  by  a  great 
23.  volume  of  minute  investigations,  which  emanated  from 

Ernst  Hein- 

rich  weber    the  schools,  and  centred  in  the  names,  of  E.  H.  Weber 


1  Du  Bois-Reymond,  'Reden,'  vol. 
ii.  p.  541,  &c. 

2  "  Whatever  cavillers  may  say, 
it  is  certain  that  histology  before 
1838,  and  histology  since  then,  are 
two  different  sciences — in  scope,  in 
purpose,  and  in  dignity — and  the 
eminent  men  to  whom  we  allude 
may  safely  answer  all  detraction  by 
a  proud  Circumspice." — Huxley  in 
his  valuable  paper  on  "  The    Cell 
Theory"  in  the  'British  and  Foreign 
Medical  Chirurgical  Review,'  1853, 
vol.  xii.  p.  290. 

3  The  three  brothers  Weber  ( Ernst 
Heinrich,     1795-1878;     Wilhelm, 
1804-91 ;  and  Eduard,  1806-71)  may 
be  looked  upon  as  early  representa- 
tives of  the  best  form  of  German 
research  on  the  lines  now  recognised 
as  the  true  and  fruitful  ones  in  na- 
tural science.    Bom  in  an  age  when 
other  great  and  more  widely  known 
reformers — such  as  Liebig,  Schiin- 
lein,  and  Joh.  Miiller — freed  them- 
selves with  difficulty  from  the  pre- 
vailing metaphysical  systems,  they 
seem   to   have  at  once   seized  the 
true  spirit  of  exact  research  with- 
out relinquishing  the  broader  philo- 
sophical and  encyclopaedic  view  of 
the  sciences  which  they  cultivated. 
Living  far  into  an  age  when  the 
utilitarian    spirit    became    equally 


seductive  in  an  opposite  direction, 
they  preserved  pure  and  undefiled 
within  themselves  the  German  ideal 
of  Wissenschaft  as  a  pursuit  carried 
on  for  its  own  intrinsic  value,  not 
for  any  immediate  practical  object. 
Their  position,  especially  that  of 
the  two  elder  brothers,  is  in  this 
respect  unique,  and  may  be  studied 
independently  of  the  scientific  ideas 
which  they  represented,  and  which 
will  occupy  us  later  on  as  a  chapter 
in  the  history  of  thought  character- 
istic of  the  German  mind  and  the 
best  type  of  the  university  studies. 
In  three  works  of  classical  value — 
'  Die  Wellenlehre  auf  Experimen- 
ten  begriindet '  (E.  H.  and  W. 
Weber),  1825;  'Die  Mechanik  der 
menschlichen  Gehwerkzeuge '  (W. 
and  E.  Weber),  1836;  '  Elektro- 
dynamische  Maasbestimmungen ' 
(W.  Weber),  1846  onward — and  in 
a  great  number  of  special  investi- 
gations, the  method  of  exact  mea- 
surement was  applied  to  physical, 
physiological,  and  even  mental 
phenomena,  and  the  foundation 
laid  for  a  mechanical  description 
and  mathematical  calculation.  The 
later  generalisations,  known  as  Wil- 
helm Weber's  law  of  electro-dyn- 
amics and  E.  H.  Weber's  law  of 
psycho-physics,  have  given  rise  to- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 


197 


and  Johannes  Miiller.     The  school  of  the  latter  especially  and  Johan- 

J    nesMuller. 

has  the  merit  of  having  introduced  over  the  whole  field 
of  physiological  phenomena  exact  methods  of  inquiry, 
of  having  established  physiological  laboratories  all  over 
Germany  similar  to  Liebig's  chemical  laboratory  at 
Giessen,  and  of  having  effectually  chased  away  the  vague 
notions  of  the  older  metaphysical  school,  and  diffused  the 
true  scientific  spirit.  It  boasts  of  having  filled  the  chairs 
of  medicine,  physiology,  and  anatomy  at  the  German 
universities  with  a  long  list  of  eminent  teachers  who  have 
spread  this  true  scientific  spirit  in  every  branch  of  the 
medical  sciences,1  which  it  has  in  consequence  drawn  into 


long  controversies  and  fruitful 
theories.  Their  joint  labours 
cover  fully  half  a  century.  See 
for  a  sympathetic  picture  of  the 
position  which  the  three  brothers 
Weber  held  in  the  learned  world 
the  biography  of  Fechner  by  Kuntze, 
1892,  p.  243:  "They  were  among 
the  first  to  raise  the  study  of  Nature 
among  Germans  to  the  eminence 
occupied  by  the  philosophers  and 
discoveries  of  the  Latin  races." 

1  The  medical  sciences,  represent- 
ed by  the  medical  faculty,  but  also 
by  those  biological  sciences  which, 
like  botany,  zoology,  anthropology, 
&c.,  belong  to  the  philosophical 
faculty,  now  furnish  the  largest 
number  of  students  to  the  German 
universities.  In  the  beginning  of 
the  century  the  theological  faculty, 
which  then  included  the  greater 
part  of  those  who  prepared  them- 
selves for  higher  teaching,  stood 
at  the  head  as  regards  numbers. 
Under  the  influence  of  the  philo- 
logico  -  historical  movement,  which 
grew  and  culminated  in  the  course 
of  this  century,  and  the  rising  tide 
of  the  exact  sciences,  the  philoso- 
phical faculty  for  a  time  gained 


and  maintained  the  upper  hand. 
Biological  —  including  medical  — 
studies  now  command  the  greatest 
attention.  In  his  statistical  report 
(contained  in  Lexis,  '  Die  deutschen 
Universitaten,'  Berlin,  1893)  Prof. 
Conrad  gives  an  interesting  table 
of  the  changing  numerical  pro- 
portion in  the  different  faculties 
(vol.  i.  p.  125,  &c.)  Prof.  Billroth 
in  his  admirable  treatise,  '  Ueber 
das  Lehren  und  Lernen  der  medi- 
cinischen  Wissenschaften,'  Vienna, 
1876,  deals  with  this  subject  at  all 
the  German  universities,  including 
the  Austrian.  As  Vienna  is  such 
an  important  centre  of  medical 
studies,  the  proportion  of  those 
students  who  cultivate  biological 
studies  would  probably  be  still 
greater  if  we  were  to  include  the 
Austrian  universities.  I  suppose 
the  figure  would  be  about  40  per 
cent  of  the  whole.  To  Billroth's 
treatise  I  may  also  refer  as  con- 
firming in  relation  to  these  more 
modern  branches  what  I  said  above 
of  the  culture  of  Wisscnschaft.  See 
p.  279  and  the  whole  section  on  the 
relation  of  the  biological  sciences  to 
the  university,  pp.  411-446.  It  is 


198 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


24. 

Psycho- 
physics. 


the  circle  of  the  exact  or  mechanical  sciences.  But  not 
only  in  its  far-reaching  applications  to  medical  know- 
ledge and  practice  has  the  movement  which  centred  in 
Weber  and  Miiller  shown  its  strength  and  importance ;  it 
has  also,  from  the  commencement,  extended  its  influence 
in  another  direction.  To  it  belongs  pre-eminently  the 
cultivation  of  that  borderland  which  connects  the  natural 
and  the  mental  sciences.  Miiller1  himself  began  his 
career  by  a  study  of  the  mechanism  of  the  perceptions 
of  the  senses.  He  affirmed  the  law  of  specific  energies, 


interesting  to  note  that  Prof.  Bill- 
roth  does  not  employ  the  word 
biological,  but  uses  the  untranslat- 
able compound  iwturtrissenschaft- 
lich-medicinisch. 

1  Johannes  Muller  (1801-58)  has 
been  termed  the  Haller  of  the 
nineteenth  century,  the  Cuvier  of 
Germany.  A  very  good  account 
of  his  work,  which  forms  an  im- 
portant chapter  in  the  history  of 
German  biology,  is  contained  in  Du 
Bois-Reymond's  '  Gedachtnissrede 
auf  Joh.  Miiller'  (1858),  reprinted 
with  extensive  notes  in  his  '  Reden,' 
vol.  ii.  pp.  143-334.  Muller  is  there 
considered  as  the  last  representa- 
tive of  a  dynasty  of  philosophers 
who  embraced  the  whole  domain  of 
"biology,"  which  since  has  become 
divided  into  various  sciences,  not- 
ably the  morphological  and  the 
physiological  branches.  He  thus 
stands  out  as  the  master  of  some 
of  the  greatest  modern  represent- 
atives of  natural  and  medical  sci- 
ence, such  as  Schwann  and  Henle 
in  anatomy,  Briicke,  Du  Bois-Rey- 
mond,  and  Helmholtz  in  physiology, 
Virchow  in  pathological  anatomy. 
He  together  with  Lucas  Schonlein 
(1793-1864)  may  be  considered  as 
the  founder  of  the  modern  Berlin 
school  of  medicine,  contemporane- 
ous with  wjiich  is  the  modern 


Austrian  school,  with  the  names  of 
Purkinje,  Skoda,  Oppolzer,  and 
Rokitansky.  An  excellent  charac- 
terisation of  the  different  positions 
and  influences,  of  the  cross-currents 
of  thought,  of  the  original  homes 
and  of  the  wanderings  of  the  scien- 
tific spirit  through  the  many  Ger- 
man -  speaking  countries  and  the 
extensive  network  of  German  uni- 
versities, will  be  found  in  Billroth, 
loc.  cit. ,  pp.  307-366.  If  we  imagine 
a  similar  life  as  existing  all  through 
the  century  in  other  domains  of 
thought — in  philosophy,  theology, 
philology,  mathematics,  chemistry, 
law,  and  the  science  of  history — we 
get  a  faint  idea  of  the  work  of  the 
German  universities.  In  Lexis, 
'Die  deutschen  Universitaten,'  an 
attempt  has  been  made  to  give 
such  a  picture.  The  picture,  how- 
ever, suffers  by  the  exclusion  of  the 
Austrian  universities,  and  these — 
notably  in  the  medical  world — hold 
such  a  very  high  position  that  the 
record  of  the  united  work  is  some- 
what incomplete.  The  sciences  are 
also  in  this  record  cut  up  into 
many  branches,  whereas  in  the 
earlier  part  of  the  century  many  of 
these  were  united  and  represented 
by  one  great  name.  Such  a  name 
was  Johannes  Muller  in  biology. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 


199 


which  declares  that  the  differences  of  the  sensations  of 
light  and  colour,  of  sound,  of  touch,  &c.,  do  not  depend 
upon  the  mode  of  irritation,  nor  even  upon  the  different 
structure  of  the  specific  nerves,  but  upon  the  nature  of 
the  central  sense  organ.  In  the  school  of  Miiller  the 
phenomena  of  voltaic  electricity,  which  had  been  so  seduc- 
tive and  misleading  to  an  earlier  school  of  physiologists 
not  experienced  in  the  methods  of  exact  research,  were 
again  -subjected  to  scientific  investigation,  and  led  to 
the  brilliant  researches  with  which  the  name  of  Du  Bois- 
Eeymond  is  so  intimately  connected.  He  is  as  ready  as 
Helmholtz,  who  in  his  two  great  works  on  physiological 
optics  and  musical  acoustics  has  founded  new  branches 
of  science,1  to  acknowledge  the  leadership  of  Johannes 


1  Helmholtz  (1821-95),  equally 
celebrated  as  physiologist  and  ma- 
thematical philosopher,  was  edu- 
cated under  the  influence  of  Jo- 
hannes Miiller  on  the  one  side,  of 
Jacobi  and  the  Konigsberg  school 
of  mathematicians  (Bessel  and  Neu- 
mann) on  the  other.  If  we  add  to 
this  that  he  also  made  a  profound 
study  of  those  far-reaching  specula- 
tions which  originated  in  the  phil- 
osophy of  Kant,  we  realise  how  rare 
is  the  combination  of  ability  and 
knowledge  which  he  has  brought  to 
bear  on  the  discussion  of  the  most 
advanced  problems  in  physics, 
biology,  and  psychology.  In  the 
sequel  I  shall  have  to  refer  so 
frequently  to  his  writings  that  I 
confine  myself  here  to  giving  the 
date  of  his  principal,  his  epoch-mak- 
ing publications  :  1847.  'Ueberdie 
Erhaltungder Kraft';  1858.  'Ueber 
die  Integrate  der  hydrodynamischen 
Gleichungen,  welche  der  Wirbel- 
bewegung  entsprechen '  —  both  re- 
printed in  '  Wissenschaftliche  Ab- 
handlungen,'  Leipzig,  1882  and 


1883,  2  vols.  These  two  Memoirs 
may  be  considered  as  corner-stones 
of  two  of  the  most  important  mo- 
dern theories  in  physical  science, 
the  "conservation  of  energy"  and 
the  "  theory  of  vortex  motion."  In 
both,  the  name  of  Helmholtz  is  in- 
timately allied  with  that  of  William 
Thomson  (Lord  Kelvin).  Equally 
important  and  more  comprehensive 
have  been  his  researches  in  the 
physiology  and  psychology  of  sense- 
perceptions  in  his  '  Physiologische 
Optik,'  Leipzig,  1867;  'Lehre  von 
den  Tonempfindungen,'  Braunsch- 
weig, 1863. 

Helmholtz  has  also  contributed 
largely  to  the  discussion  of  two  very 
important  branches  of  modern  spe- 
culation— first,  the  theoretical  views 
on  the  nature  of  electrical  pheno- 
mena expressed  by  the  opposite 
conceptions  of  Wilhelm  Weber  in 
Germany  and  Faraday  in  England  ; 
second,  the  origin  of  geometrical 
axioms,  especially  the  axiom  refer- 
ring to  parallel  lines.  A  great 
interest  in  this  subject  had  been 


200 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


Miiller.  And  out  of  the  circle  of  which  E.  H.  Weber 
was  the  centre,  has  emanated  that  work  of  Fechner, 
'Elements  of  Psycho-physics,'  which  marks  an  epoch 
in  psychology:  it  is  indeed  mainly  occupied  with  the  ex- 
position and  application  of  what  is  termed  Weber's  law 
of  sensation.1  In  the  course  of  the  second  quarter  of  the 
century,  the  names  of  Gauss  and  Jacobi  in  mathematics, 
of  Liebig  and  Wohler  in  chemistry,  of  Schleiden  and 
Schwann  in  the  science  of  life,  of  Miiller  and  Weber  in 
physiology,  raised  German  science  to  the  level  previ- 
ously reached  by  the  French  Academicians,  by  Laplace 
and  Lagrange,  by  Lavoisier  and  Berthollet,  by  Cuvier 
and  St-Hilaire,  by  Vicq-d'Azyr  and  Bichat.  During 


created  by  the  posthumous  publi- 
cation of  Riemann's  celebrated  Me- 
moir, '  Ueber  die  Hypothesen  welche 
der  Geometric  zu  Grunde  liegen,' 
Gottingen,  1865.  Helmholtz's  in- 
vention of  the  ophthalmoscope  in 
1851  marks  an  epoch  in  ophthal- 
mology. 

1  Gustav  Theodor  Fechner  (1806- 
87),  professor  at  the  University  of 
Leipsic,  was  an  extraordinary  man. 
The  wide  range  of  his  interests  and 
his  great  personal  influence  are  well 
described  in  his  biography  by  Dr 
Kuntze,  '  G.  T.  Fechner,  Ein 
deutsches  Gelehrtenleben,'  Leipzig, 
1892.  Together  with  Lotze  he  may 
be  said  to  have  brought  about  the 
reform  of  German  speculative  phil- 
osophy, and  in  relation  to  this  he 
will  occupy  our  attention  largely 
in  a  later  portion  of  this  book.  He 
belonged  to  the  circle  of  which  E. 
H.  Weber  was  the  centre,  and  has 
taken  an  important  place  in  the 
history  of  philosophy  and  science 
by  his  now  celebrated  work,  '  Ele- 
mente  der  Psychophysik,'  2  vols., 
Leipzig,  1860  ;  2nd  ed.,  1890.  The 


object  of  this  work  is  to  establish 
"an  exact  doctrine  of  the  relations 
of  body  and  mind,"  the  principal 
task  being  "to  fix  the  measure  of 
psychical  quantities."  He  says  in 
the  preface  :  "  The  empirical  law 
which  forms  the  principal  founda- 
tion, was  laid  down  long  ago 
by  different  students  in  different 
branches,  and  was  expressed  with 
comparative  generality  mainly  by 
E.  H.  Weber,  whom  I  would 
call  the  father  of  psycho-physics" 
(Preface,  p.  v).  In  early  life 
Fechner  did  much,  by  his  transla- 
tions of  Biot's  '  Physics '  and  The'- 
nard's  '  Chemistry,'  as  well  as  by  his 
own  experimental  works,  to  intro- 
duce the  French  scientific  spirit  into 
German  research.  His  psycho-phy- 
sical labours  have  been  continued 
by  Prof.  Wundt ;  his  importance 
as  marking  a  turning  -  point  in 
German  philosophy  is  brought  out 
in  Paulsen's  '  Einleitung  in  die 
Philosophic,'  Berlin,  1890.  See 
especially  Preface,  p.  viii,  and  p. 
318,  where  Fechner  is  placed  before 
Lotze. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT    IN    GERMANY. 


201 


the  second  half  of  the  century,  the  influence  of  French 
thought  on  German  science  has  been  less  marked,  partly 
owing  to  the  independent  course  which  the  latter,  since 
the  age  of  Johannes  Miiller,  has  struck  out  for  herself 
in  the  biological  sciences,  partly  through  the  more  inti- 
mate intercourse  which  has  set  in  between  English  and 
German  thought.  The  three  great  scientific  ideas  which 
the  second  half  of  the  century  has  been  establishing  —  the 
law  of  the  conservation  of  energy,  Darwin's  theory  of 
descent,  and  Faraday's  novel  conception  of  electrical 
phenomena  —  have  been  elaborated  mainly  by  the  co- 
operation of  English  and  German  research,  though  it 
must  be  admitted  that  at  least  one  of  these  developments 
dates  back  to  the  beginnings  laid  by  French  science,1 
whilst  the  views  of  Faraday  are  subversive  of  some  of 
the  fundamental  notions  to  which  the  works  of  the  great 
French  mathematicians  had  given  very  general  currency. 
Before  we  can  enter  more  fully  on  a  review  of  these  more 
modern  ideas,  I  must,  however,  give  a  picture  of  the  state 
of  scientific  thought  in  England  during  the  first  half  of 
the  century.  This  will  be  our  subject  in  the  last  portion 
of  the  present  section. 


1  Darwin's  theory  of  descent  has 
its  forerunners  in  Lamarck  and  St- 
Hilaire,  whose  merits  in  this  re- 
spect are  supposed  to  have  been 
overlooked  owing  to  the  overwhelm- 
ing authority  of  Cuvier.  See  Hux- 
ley, ' '  Origin  of  Species  "  in  '  Lay 
Sermons,'  1891,  p.  252;  "Evolu- 
tion in  Biology "  in  '  Science  and 
Culture,'  1888,  pp.  296,  313.  But 
whilst  it  is  true  that  Lamarck  and 
St-Hilaire  entertained  doubts  as  to 
the  fixity  of  species,  the  explana- 
tion of  the  particular  manner  in 
which  the  change  of  species  takes 


place  is  entirely  due  to  Darwin, 
and  without  this  further  step 
speculations  as  to  the  origin  of 
species  would  have  remained  for  a 
long  time  in  the  vague.  Lamarck's 
speculations  were  of  no  real  use  to 
Darwin,  and  had  besides  been  anti- 
cipated by  Erasmus  Darwin.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  researches  of 
Sadi  Carnot  were  of  great  value  in 
the  hands  of  Joule,  Thomson,  and 
Helmholtz,  who  may  be  regarded 
as  the  founders  of  the  doctrine  of 
the  conservation  of  energy. 


202  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

25.  But  it  is  my  object  at  present  not  so  much  to  dwell 

Spirit  of  ex- 

actraearch  upon  specific  ideas  or  doctrines  as  on  the  growth,  the 

and  Wissen- 

diffusion,  and  the  general  character  of  scientific  thought, 
as  this  has  been  established  by  the  separate  contributions 
of  the  three  nations  in  the  course  of  the  first  half  of  our 
century.  I  therefore  cannot  leave  the  subject  of  German 
science  without  still  more  precisely  noting  the  peculiar 
character  which  scientific  thought  has  assumed  under 
the  influence  of  the  German  university  system.  As 
we  saw  before,  when  the  spirit  of  exact  research,  mainly 
through  the  influence  of  the  great  French  mathema- 
ticians and  physicists,  became  diffused  in  Germany, 
and  entered  the  pale  of  the  German  universities,  it  was 
met  there  by  that  peculiar  ideal  of  learning  which  the 
German  language  terms  Wissenschaft.  This  encounter 
did  not  everywhere  produce  a  favourable  reception  for 
the  new  school ;  but  in  the  end  it  led,  like  every  con- 
troversy, to  a  firmer  establishment  of  the  true  princi- 
ples of  research.  The  life  of  the  German  universities 
had  in  the  earlier  centuries  begun  with  classical  studies ; 
it  had  been  reformed  under  the  influence  of  the  theo- 
logical and  juridical  requirements  of  the  Protestant 
Governments ;  and  ultimately  it  had  been  entirely  re- 
newed under  the  influence  of  the  classical  and  philo- 
sophical studies  centred  in  the  fourth  or  philosophical 
faculty.  These  classical  and  philosophical  studies  com- 
bined to  create  the  ideal  of  Wissenschaft,  or  science,  in 
the  broadest  sense  of  the  word.  This  ideal  formed  the 
central  conception  in  the  new  scheme  of  a  higher  and 
general  education  of  the  nation ;  it  accompanied  the 
great  revival  in  art,  poetry,  and  literature.  In  the 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN    GERMANY.           203 

philosophy  of  Kant  and  Fichte,  the  republican  notions 
which  led  the  political  movements  in  America  and 
France  had  been  reduced  to  a  system  and  theoretically 
proved ;  the  discipline  of  a  classical  education  was  the 
school  in  which  leaders  and  youths  were  trained  who 
marched  into  the  war  against  the  great  oppressor.  This 
ideal  of  Wissenschaft  had  thus  acquired  a  practical  mean- 
ing, an  ethical — not  to  say  a  religious — significance ;  it 
was  allied  to  the  religious  revival  preached  by  Schleier- 
macher  and  a  section  of  the  Eomantic  school.  Of  its 
value  as  a  principle  for  guiding  research  and  learn- 
ing it  had  given  proof  in  that  great  circle  of  studies 
which,  since  the  time  of  F.  A.  Wolf  and  Wilhelm  von 
Humboldt,  was  comprised  under  the  name  of  Philology. 
Under  its  influence  new  universities  were  being  founded 
and  academies  remodelled. 

Now,  it  is  the  peculiarity  of  all  philosophical  and 
historical  studies  that  they  deal  with  one  great  subject, 
which  cannot  easily  be  divided  into  a  number  of  inde- 
pendent parts  capable  of  separate  treatment ;  since  their 
interest  attaches  mainly  to  the  fact  that  they  explore 
the  workings  and  manifestations  of  the  human  mind  in 
the  past  and  in  the  present.  These  studies  are  there- 
fore forced  to  keep  always  in  the  foreground  the  idea 
of  a  great  unity  of  action  and  purpose,  to  aim  at  com- 
pleteness of  view,  and  to  refer  all  special  researches  to 
general  principles  and  standards.  The  encyclopaedic  view,  20. 
in  fact,  is  forced  upon  all  philosophical  and  historical  pwdicview 

necessary  in 

sciences.     Almost  without  exception  the  great  masters  philosophy 

and  history. 

and  teachers  who  lived  in  the  beginning  of  this  century 
adhered  to  this  view,  and  however  great  in  special  and 


204  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

detailed  research,  measured  the  importance  of  their 
results  according  to  the  light  which  they  were  able  to 
throw  upon  the  questions  referring  to  the  whole  subject 
and  its  combined  life  and  unity. 

It  was  also  natural,  seeing  that  this  comprehensive 
or  philosophical  treatment  led  to  such  great  results  in 
the  historical  sciences,  that  an  attempt  should  have  been 
made  to  deal  with  the  phenomena  of  Nature  by  a  similar 
conception.  It  was  not  a  new  or  a  far-fetched  sugges- 
tion to  regard  Nature  as  the  playground  of  a  hidden 
intelligence,  of  an  unconscious  mind,  just  as  history,  lan- 
guage, and  thought  were  viewed  as  the  manifestations 
of  the  conscious  human  mind.  After  this  the  further 
conception  was  not  remote  that  both  the  mind  of  Nature 
and  the  mind  of  Man  are  only  two  different  sides  of  the 
universal  or  absolute  Mind.  The  philosophy  of  Sfihelling 
was  the  first  attempt  to  put  this  idea  into  an  applicable/ 
form,  the  system  of  Hegel  the  first  confident  elaboration 
of  it  in  its  various  ramifications  and  applications.  At 
the  time  when  the  mathematical  and  physical  sciences 
were  leading  the  way  in  France,  and  gradually  forcing 
their  way  into  Germany,  most  of  the  universities  in  the 
latter  country  had  one  or  more  representatives  of  that 
new  and  apparently  promising  school  which  termed  itself 
27.  the  "Philosophy  of  Nature."  The  trammels  of  this  school 

Philosophy 

of  Nature,  had  to  be  shaken  off  by  those  who,  as  they  became 
gradually  convinced  of  its  barrenness  in  actual  results, 
took  up  the  cause  of  the  exact  or  mathematical  sciences 
now  that  they  had  been  cultivated  by  many  isolated 
labourers  in  Germany  and  in  England,  and  had  been 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN    GERMANY. 


205 


for  the  first  time  connected  into  a  great  organisation  by 
the  French  Academy  of  Sciences. 

The  opposition  in  which  the  new  school  of  exact  and 
detailed  research  stood  to  the  representatives  of  the  broad 
philosophical  view  gave  rise  to  a  great  many  currents 
of  thought;  for  neither  the  former  nor  the  latter  pre- 
sented a  united  front.  Among  those  who  advocated  the 
exact  methods  of  research  there  was  a  section  which 
clung  more  exclusively  to  the  empirical  side,  and  culti- 
vated the  descriptive  and  experimental  sciences ;  whereas 
others,  whom  we  may  call  the  French  school  of  science, 
developed  the  mathematical  methods,  not  without  a  cer- 
tain ill-disguised  contempt  for  pure  empiricism.1  On 
the  side  of  classical  and  philosophical  studies  there  was 
a  section  which  cultivated  the  historical 2  in  contradis- 


28. 

Conflict  be> 
tween  the 
scientific 
and  the 
philosophi- 
cal views. 


1  On  the  relations  of  mathemati- 
cal and  experimental  physics,  and 
the  different  opinions  which  existed 
during  the  first  half  of  the  century, 
see  Helmholtz's  popular  addresses 
in  many  places,  but  especially  the 
discourse  on  Gustav  Magnus  (1802- 
70),  who  may  be  regarded  as  a 
representative  of  the  experimental 
school  in  Germany.  In  the  opin- 
ion of  this  school,  which  cultivated 
the  borderland  of  physics  and  chem- 
istry, of  organic  and  inorganic  phe- 
nomena, or  investigated  the  less 
known  phenomena  of  frictional  elec- 
tricity (Riess)  or  the  complicated 
phenomena  of  meteorology  (Dove), 
a  danger  existed  that  mathematical 
theories  and  elaborate  calculations 
might  lead  to  an  estrangement  from 
nature  and  observation,  similar  to 
that  which  speculative  philosophy 
had  created  before.  Helmholtz  him- 
self was  met  by  this  sentiment  when 
he  published  his  great  memoir, 


'Ueber  die  Erhaltung  der  Kraft,' 
in  1847 ;  Poggendorf's  physical 
periodical  would  not  receive  it, 
and  Jacobi,  the  mathematician, 
was  the  only  one  who  showed  any 
interest  in  it.  See  Helmholtz, 
'  Wisseuschaftliche  Abhandlungen,' 
vol.  i.  p.  73;  'Reden,'  vol.  ii.  p. 
46. 

2  As  the  philosophy  of  Schelling 
promoted  a  study  of  nature,  and  in 
doing  so  prepared  its  own  downfall, 
so  the  philosophy  of  Hegel  led  to  a 
study  of  history,  and  thus  to  the 
proof  of  the  insufficiency  of  its  own 
generalisations.  Many  valuable  be- 
ginnings of  historical  research  eman- 
ated also  from  the  Romantic  school 
of  literature.  In  all  these  instances 
philosophical  interests  led  beyond 
the  abstract  logical  and  metaphysical 
treatment  into  the  broad  and  fertile 
plains  of  actual  life,  be  it  that  of 
nature  or  of  art  or  of  history.  But 
the  true  methods  of  research  in 


206 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


29. 

Alexander 
von  Hum- 
boldt. 


tinction  to  the  philosophical  view,  and  another  which 
elaborated  what  it  termed  exclusively  the  critical  meth- 
ods,1 not  without  a  certain  suspicion  regarding  those  who 
showed  a  desire  to  roam  into  outlying  fields  which  did 
not  permit  of  equally  strict  discipline  and  treatment.  So 
far  as  this  refers  to  the  purely  historical  sciences,  I 
shall  revert  to  the  subject  when  I  come  to  treat  of  the 
principles  which  underlie  and  guide  this  line  of  studies. 
At  present  I  am  concerned  with  the  growth  and  dif- 
fusion of  the  exact  scientific  spirit  and  its  methods. 

No  one  did  more  to  spread  the  ideas  and  methods  of 
French  science  in  Germany  than  Alexander  von  Hum- 
boldt.  He  himself  had  done  original  scientific  work2  be- 


these  extensive  fields  were  after- 
wards found  not  so  much  in  philo- 
sophical canons  as  in  a  love  of  detail 
and  observation,  and  in  the  exercise 
of  an  unbiassed  criticism  of  facts 
and  records.  For  the  relations  of 
philosophy  to  history  in  respect  of 
this,  see  Wegele,  '  Geschichte  der 
deutschen  Historiographie,'  Miin- 
chen,  1885,  5th  book,  p.  975,  &c. 
Equally  important  are — Gervinus, 
'  Grundziige  der  Historik,'  Leipzig, 
1837  ;  the  '  Nekrolog  auf  Schlosser,' 
Leipzig,  1862,  including  the  whole 
literature  which  it  provoked ;  and 
0.  Lorenz,  '  Die  Geschichtswissen- 
schaft,'  Berlin,  '1886,  especially  the 
first  chapter. 

]  On  the  Critical  school  of  phil- 
ology, and  the  wider  and  narrower 
sense  in  which  the  aims  and  meth- 
ods of  the  science  of  antiquity  were 
defined,  see  Bursiau, '  Geschichte  der 
classischen  Philologie  in  Deutsch- 
land,'  Munchen  und  Leipzig,  1883, 
p.  665,  &c.  ;  also  0.  Ribbeck,  '  Fried- 
rich  Ritschl,'  Leipzig,  1879  and 
1880.  Further,  the  essays  on  Bockh, 
K.  0.  Muller,  and  Georg  Curtius  in 
the  third  volume  of  Ernst  Curtius, 


'  Alterthum  und  Gegenwart,'  Berlin, 
1889  ;  and,  finally,  the  chapter  on 
"  Klassische  Philologie  "  by  Wila- 
mowitz-Mollendorf  in  Lexis,  '  Die 
deutschen  Universitaten, '  vol.  i.  p. 
457,  &c. 

2  Alexander  von  Humboldt  (1769- 
1859)  published  in  1797,  shortly  after 
Galvani's  great  discovery,  his  '  Ver- 
suche  iiber  die  gereizte  Muskel-  und 
Nervenfaser.'  In  the  history  of  sci- 
ence his  name  will  live  as  that  of 
the  man  who  organised  that  "  scien- 
tific conspiracy  of  nations  "  which  is 
peculiar  to  our  century,  and  with- 
out which  the  study  of  geography, 
meteorology,  astronomy,  the  phe- 
nomena of  tides  and  magnetic  dis- 
turbances— called  by  him  magnetic 
storms  —  could  not  effectually  be 
carried  on.  The  fact  also  that  on 
his  return  from  his  great  travels  he 
became  next  to  Napoleon  Bona- 
parte the  most  famous  man  in 
Europe,  did  more  than  anything 
else  to  raise  the  natural  sciences  in 
the  popular  mind  to  that  eminence 
which  earlier  belonged  to  polite 
literature. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY. 


207 


fore  he  left  Germany  for  the  extensive  travels  by  which 
he  became  celebrated,  and  through  which  he  founded  a 
new  science — the  science  that  deals  with  the  geographical 
distribution  of  plant  life.  Moreover,  his  absence  from  his 
native  country  fell  within  that  period  during  which  the 
philosophical  school,  headed  by  Schelling  and  Hegel,  at- 
tained to  its  greatest  power.  He  was  never  drawn  into  its 
vortex ;  on  the  contrary,  he  maintained  a  lifelong  protest 
against  the  spirit  of  its  doctrine  at  a  time  when  the  circle 
which  surrounded  him  at  Berlin  came  under  its  powerful 
influence.1  He  led  a  long  line  of  ardent  young  workers 
both  to  the  right  sources  of  scientific  knowledge  and 
to  an  ultimate  victory  over  the  opposed  school  of 
thought.  Though  not  a  profound  mathematician  him- 
self, he  appreciated  the  part  which  mathematics  were 
destined  to  play  in  science.  Among  other  things,  he 
protected  and  encouraged  younger  mathematical  talents, 
and  tried  to  draw  Gauss  from  the  solitary  heights  which 
he  inhabited  into  the  midst  of  the  scientific  circles  of 
the  day.2  Then  there  was  the  graat  influence  which 


1  Cf.  p.  178,  note  1.  It  has  latterly 
become  the  fashion  to  say  so  much 
against  the  mistaken  methods  of  the 
Naturphilosophie  that  it  is  well  to 
remember  how  many  men  of  fore- 
most rank  in  the  natural  sciences 
belonged  at  one  time  to  this  school 
or  were  influenced  by  it.  Foremost 
of  all  stands  Oken  (1779-1851),  the 
founder  of  the  German  Association 
of  Science,  and  editor  of  the  peri- 
odical 'Isis.'  Further,  the  compara- 
tive anatomist  Carus  (1789-1869) ; 
Oersted  (1777-1851),  the  discoverer 
of  electro-magnetism ;  Kielmeyer, 
the  friend  of  Cuvier  (1765-1844) ; 
Ignaz  Dollinger  (1770-1841),  one  of 


the  earliest  evolutionists ;  D.  G. 
Kieser  (1779-1862),  a  medical 
teacher  of  great  influence.  More 
or  less  influenced  by  the  teachings 
of  this  school  were  Goethe  (1749- 
1832) ;  Karl  Ernst  von  Baer  (1792- 
1876),  whose  impartial  opinion  on 
the  Naturphilosophie  as  early  as 
1821  is  important.  Further,  Lie- 
big  (1803-73);  Johannes  Miiller 
(1801-58) ;  Roschlaub  (1768-1835)  ; 
Schonlein  (1793-1864),  the  founder 
of  what  is  called  the  ' '  natural- 
history  "  school  of  medicine. 

2  See  A.  von  Humboldt's  Life  by 
Bruhns,  translated  by  Lassell,  1873, 
vol.  ii.  p.  145  sqq. 


208 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


so.       Berzelius  exerted  on  German  science  through  his  teach- 

Tnfluence  of 

r  and  his  writings.     From  him  emanated  that  great 


on  German 

science. 


perfection  of  the  purely  experimental  methods  which 
in  his  own  hands,  as  well  as  in  those  of  Wohler,  Mit- 
scherlich,  Magnus,  and  others,  led  to  an  accumulation 
of  detailed  knowledge  in  chemistry  of  unforeseen  im- 
portance and  magnitude.  His  own  annual  reports,  as 
well  as  Gmelin's  celebrated  handbook  of  chemistry,  are 
monuments  of  this  unparalleled  industry. 

Others,  like  Liebig,  Johannes  Mtiller,  Lucas  Sehoulein, 
freed  themselves  under  the  influence  of  French  science,1 
or  by  their  own  deeper  insight,  from  the  sway  of  the 
false  and  misleading  philosophy  to  which  they  had  at 
one  time  listened.  A  third  section  started  from  philo- 
sophical premisses,  but  from  premisses  opposed  to  the 
doctrines  of  Schelling  and  Hegel. 

The  school  of  Fries,2  in  which  Schleiden  was  the  most 


1  English  science  had  an  import- 
ant but  less  marked  influence  on 
the  development  of  naturalistic  and 
medical  studies  in  Germany.  So 
far  as  the  latter  especially  are  con- 
cerned, see  Billroth,  '  Ueber  das 
Lehren  und  Lernen  der  rnedici- 
nischen  Wissenschaften  an  den 
Universitaten  der  deutschen  Na- 
tion,' Wien,  1876,  p.  33.  He 
roughly  divides  the  medical  schools 
of  Germany  into  two  groups,  both 
descending  from  Boerhaave :  the 
one,  the  modern  Berlin  school  of 
Miiller,  Schonlein,  Romberg,  and 
Virchow,  through  Haller,  Reil, 
Hufeland,  and  Roschlaub ;  the 
other,  the  modern  Vienna  school 
of  Oppolzer,  Rokitansky,  and  Bill- 
roth,  through  Gerhard  von  Swiet- 
en,  De  Haen,  Stoll,  Frank,  Pur- 
kinje,  and  Skoda.  Of  French 
names  •which  had  great  influence 


he  gives  Broussais,  Corvisart,  Bayle, 
Cruveilhier,  and  Laennec ;  of  Eng- 
lish, John  Hunter,  Matthew  Bailie, 
and  Astley  Cooper.  He  gives  also 
the  name  of  Immanuel  Kant  as 
an  important  influence  in  the  de- 
velopment of  the  German  schools  of 
medicine. 

2  Jacob  Fries  (1773-1843)  pro- 
fessor at  Heidelberg  and  Jena,  led 
the  critical  philosophy  of  Kant  into 
the  channels  of  psychology  and  an- 
thropology. During  the  heyday  of 
transcendental  philosophy,  the  phil- 
osophy of  Fries,  like  that  of  the 
Scotch  school,  was  regarded  with 
contempt  by  Hegel,  and  even  by 
Herbart,  the  opponent  of  Hegel.  It 
succeeded,  however,  in  the  end  in 
influencing  a  considerable  number 
of  philosophical  minds,  who  carried 
philosophical  thought  into  the  in- 
ductive sciences.  Besides  the  psy- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN    GERMANY. 


209 


illustrious  name,  carried  on  within  the  pale  of  the 
philosophical  school  of  science  itself  a  successful  opposi- 
tion to  the  philosophy  of  Nature.1  But  whilst  much  good 
and  sound  work  was  done  by  many  who  were  content 
to  remain  outside  of  the  favoured  studies  which  set  the 
tone  of  university  culture  during  the  classical  and  philo- 
sophical period  of  German  thought,  the  great  attack 
upon  the  mistaken  canons  of  the  philosophy  of  Nature  si. 

Philosophy 

came   from    that    science   which   had   probably   suffered  of  Nature 

and  medical 

more   than   any   other    under   the  baneful   influence   of science- 
hollow  theories  and  empty  phraseology. 

Helmholtz  describes  the  despair  which  had  taken  hold 
of  thinking  minds  in  the  medical  profession  2  :  "  My  edu- 
cation fell  within  a  period  of  the  development  of  medi- 
cine when  among  thinking  and  conscientious  minds  there 
reigned  perfect  despair.  It  was  not  difficult  to  under- 
stand that  the  older  and  mostly  theorising  methods  of 
treating  medical  subjects  had  become  absolutely  useless. 
But  with  the  theories  the  facts  which  underlay  them 
were  so  indissolubly  entangled  that  these  two  were  mostly 
cast  overboard.  How  the  science  must  be  newly  built  up 
the  example  of  the  other  natural  sciences  had  made  clear, 
but  yet  the  new  task  stood  of  giant-height  before  us.  A 
beginning  was  hardly  made,  and  the  first  beginnings  were 


chologist  Beneke  and  the  theologian 
De  Wette,  these  were  principally 
members  of  the  Jena  school,  Apelt, 
Schlomilch,  and  others,  who  edited 
'  Abhandlungen  der  Fries'schen 
Schule,'  Jena,  1847  ;  and  foremost 
among  them  Schleiden,  the  reformer 
of  botany  in  Germany.  Schleiden's 
great  work  appeared  with  the  title 
'  Botanik  als  inductive  Wissenschaft. ' 
It  opened  with  a  philosophical  in- 

VOL.  I. 


troduction  of  131  pages,  in  which 
inductive  reasoning  is  recommended 
in  opposition  at  once  to  the  trans- 
cendental NaturpJiilosophie,  and  to 
dry  empiricism.  See  Sachs,  '  Ges- 
chichte  der  Botauik,'  p.  203,  &c. 

1  See  Schleiden,  '  Schilling's  und 
Hegel's  Verhaltniss  zur  Naturwis- 
senschaft,'  Leipzig,  1844. 

2  See  Helmholtz,  'Vortritge  und 
Reden,'  vol.  i.  p.  361. 

0 


210 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


often  very  crude.  We  cannot  wonder  if  many  honest, 
serious,  thinking  men  then  turned  away  in  dissatisfaction 
from  medicine,  or  if  they  from  principle  embraced  an 
extreme  empiricism." l  "  But  the  right  kind  of  work 
brought  forth  its  fruits  much  sooner  than  many  had 
hoped.  The  introduction  of  mechanical  notions  into  the 
theories  of  circulation  and  respiration,  a  better  insight 
into  the  phenomena  of  heat,  the  more  minutely  elabor- 
ated physiology  of  the  nerves,  speedily  produced  practical 
results  of  the  greatest  importance ;  the  microscopical  ex- 
amination of  parasitic  tissues,  the  stupendous  development 
of  pathological  anatomy,  led  irresistibly  from  nebulous 
theories  to  real  facts."  And  again2:  "Whilst  in  the 
investigation  of  inorganic  nature  the  different  nations  of 
Europe  progressed  pretty  evenly,  the  recent  development 
of  physiology  and  medicine  belongs  pre-eminently  to 
Germany.  The  questions  regarding  the  principle  of  life 


1  Cf.  Helmholtz,  ibid.,  voL  ii. 
p.  178,  in  his  discourse  "Ueber  das 
Denken  in  der  Medicin  "  :  "At  that 
time  there  were  many  among  the 
younger  doctors  who,  in  despair 
about  their  science,  gave  up  all 
therapeutics,  and  took  to  empiri- 
cism, such  as  was  then  taught  by 
Rademacher.  This  on  principle 
regarded  as  vain  all  hope  of  scien- 
tific insight."  Not  only  the  ex- 
treme empiricism  of  Rademacher 
(1772-1850),  but  still  more  the  wild 
theories  of  Hahnemann  (1755-1843) 
found  during  this  age  of  general 
unsettlement  many  followers.  See 
on  the  origin,  the  principles,  and 
the  spread  of  homoeopathy,  Haser, 
'  Geschichte  der  Medicin,'  vol.  ii.  p. 
793,  &c.  Hiiser  gives  the  year  1816 
as  the  date  at  which  Hahnemann's 
doctrines  began  to  be  accepted  in 
wider  circles.  "It  must  not  be 


forgotten  that  the  heyday  of  ho- 
moeopathy fell  in  that  age  when 
medicine,  especially  in  Germany, 
was  in  a  very  deficient  state,  so 
that  the  accusations  raised  by 
Hahnemann  and  his  adherents  did 
not  appear  quite  unfounded.  It  is 
even  to  be  admitted  that  homoeo- 
pathy has  contributed  to  the  re- 
action through  which  in  our  times 
the  regeneration  of  the  art  of  heal- 
ing has  been  brought  about,  though 
this  would  have  taken  place  with- 
out Hahnemann"  (p.  803).  Homoeo- 
pathy has  no  scientific  represen- 
tative at  any  of  the  German 
universities,  and  yet  it  is  admitted 
that  it  "still  enjoys  a  great  repu- 
tation in  some  influential  circles 
among  the  general  public"  (Hirsch, 
'  Gesch.  d.  medicinischen  Wissen- 
schaften,'  p.  570). 

2  Helmholtz,  loc.  cit.,  vol.  i.  p.  362. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY.          211 

are  closely  allied  to  psychological  and  ethical  questions. 
To  start  with,  here  also  that  untiring  industry  is  required 
which  applies  itself  to  pure  science  for  purely  ideal  pur- 
poses, without  immediate  prospects  of  practical  usefulness. 
And  indeed  we  may  glory  in  the  fact  that  in  this  German 
scholars  have  always  distinguished  themselves  by  their 
enthusiastic  and  self-renouncing  diligence,  which  labours 
for  inner  satisfaction  and  not  for  outer  success." 

This  habit  of  self-renouncing  labour,  of  singleness  of       32. 

Science  for 

purpose — in  short,  the  ideal  of  pure  science  and  its  pur-  its  own  sake, 
suit — had  been  elaborated  in  many  a  secluded  workshop 
of  a  retired  German  university  mainly  under  the  influence 
of  the  classical  and  philosophical  studies  of  the  end  of 
the  last  and  the  beginning  of  the  present  century.  It  was 
held  up  high  and  conspicuous  by  the  priests  of  humanity, 
beginning  with  Lessing,  Herder,  and  Kant,  and  ending  in 
Schleiermacher,  Hermann,  and  Bockh,  at  the  head  of  a 
great  army  of  devoted  followers,  travelling  through  the 
wilderness  of  national  depression,  barbarism,  and  despair 
into  the  promised  land  of  freedom,  culture,  and  hope. 
Such  an  ideal  is  of  priceless  worth,  and  it  is  this  ideal 
which  the  philosophical  and  classical  school  of  thought 
bequeathed  during  the  first  half  of  the  century  to  that 
new  school  of  thinkers  which  was  destined  to  study,  in 
an  equally  patient  and  unselfish  spirit,  the  seemingly  less 
elevated,  but  not  less  mysterious  and  fascinating,  prob- 
lems of  Nature.  Truly  Gauss,  Weber,  and  Johannes 
Miiller  worthily  headed  the  new  army  of  labourers. 

But  though  the  elevated  spirit  in  which  scientific  work  Eev^t  ot 
is  carried  on  may  be  the  most  valuable  bequest  of  the  andCphiio-al 
classical   and   philosophical  to  the  exact  and   empirical  Iciio 


212  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

school,  there  were  certain  more  tangible  characteristics 
of  German  research,  which  were  carried  over  from  the 
older  to  the  modern  type  of  thought.  It  will  be  useful 
to  define  these  more  clearly. 

In  the  course  of  the  second  half  of  the  eighteenth 
century  German  literature  and  German  philosophy  had 
started  from  the  beginnings  laid  by  other  nations,  and 
after  mastering  and  appropriating  their  achievements, 
had  set  out  for  a  new  course  and  a  higher  flight.  Milton 
and  Shakespeare l  in  epic  and  dramatic  poetry ;  Ossian, 
the  Percy  Ballads,  and  Burns  in  song  and  lyric ;  Gibbon 
in  history ;  Joseph  Scaliger  and  Bentley  in  philology ; 
Locke,  Hume,  and  Spinoza  in  philosophy ;  Eousseau  in 
prose, — all  these  great  names  of  a  later  or  earlier  past 
had  become  familiar  watchwords  to  German  poets  or 
students — to  Lessing,  Herder,  and  Goethe,  to  Schlegel, 
F.  A.  Wolf,  and  Wilhelm  von  Humboldt,  to  Bockh,  Her- 
mann, and  Niebuhr,  to  Kant,  Fichte,  and  Jacobi,  before 
they  came  forward  with  their  own  creations.  The  same 
cosmopolitan  spirit  of  looking  elsewhere  and  everywhere 
for  beginnings,  and  for  co-operation  in  the  united  work 
of  learning ;  the  same  historical  taste,  the  same  desire  to 
glean  from  all  quarters, — characterised  the  early  decades 
of  the  revival  of  German  science.  Hence  the  many 
periodicals  and  annual  reports ;  hence  the  fact  that  the 

1  These  names  are  not  given  as  j    German      readers     only     through 

they  follow  in  time,   but  as  they  I    Goethe    and    Schlegel.      Similarly 

followed  in  their  influence  on  Ger-  <    the  reaction  against  the  school  of 

man  thought  and  literature.     Thus  -    Leibniz    and  Wolff  in    philosophy 

the    early    representatives    of    the  began  with  Kant's  reply  to  Hume's 

German  revival  were  influenced  by  sceptical   philosophy,    whereas   the 

Milton  and  Pope  more  than  by  the  i   study  of  Spinoza  influenced  Kant's 

greater  Shakespeare :  epic  and  di-  followers    and    opponents,    Jacobi, 

dactic   preceded    dramatic   poetry  :  !    Fichte,  and  Schelling. 

Shakespeare  was  made  familiar  to  I 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   GERMANY. 


213 


nation  which  requires  them  least1  possesses  the  most 
and  the  best  translations  of  foreign  authors.  But  the 
quality  of  greatest  value  for  science  which  springs  from 
the  cosmopolitan  and  historical  spirit  is  that  of  complete- 
ness and  thoroughness  of  research. 

Secondly,  the  German  man  of  science  was  not  only 
thorough,  but  was  as  little  as  the  German  philosopher 
or  classicist  had  been,  an  isolated  thinker.  He  was 
neither  the  member  of  an  academy  only,  nor  a  solitary 
genius  reduced  to  the  resources  of  his  own  study.  He 
lived  mostly  at  a  university,  surrounded  by  others,  whose 
labours  came  in  contact  with  his  own,  or  who  treated  the 
same  subject  from  a  different  point  of  view.  He  had  thus 
to  define  the  limits  of  his  science,  and  to  see  that  no  part 
of  the  common  field  was  left  uncultivated  and  unexplored. 
His  object  could  not  be  to  produce  simply  a  work  of  indi- 
vidual greatness  or  of  finished  artistic  merit ;  his  work 
was  an  integral  portion  of  the  one  great  science;  his 


34. 

Complete- 
ness and 
thorough- 
ness of  re- 
search. 


1  This  must  not  be  misunder- 
stood. A  knowledge  of  the  master- 
pieces of  foreign  literature  was  as 
necessary  to  the  development  of 
the  German  mind  as  it  is  to  that 
of  any  other  nation  ;  it  was  and 
is  more  complete  there  than  in  any 
other  country  :  what  I  mean  is, 
that  as  a  knowledge  of  French  and 
English  has  been  for  a  long  time 
so  common  among  the  educated 
classes  in  Germany,  translations  are 
more  easily  dispensed  with  there 
than  in  other  countries.  In  spite 
of  that,  German  literature  abounds 
in  excellent  translations  of  the 
classics  of  France  and  England 
both  in  general  literature  and  in 
science.  It  is  also  interesting  to 
note  that  no  modern  language 
has  succeeded  so  well  in  imitating 
foreign  and  classical  metres  as  .the 


German,  hexameters  having  become 
domiciled  in  Germany  through  Voss 
and  Goethe,  the  Alcaic  and  Sapphic 
metres  through  Klopstock  and  Her- 
der, the  more  complicated  stanzas 
through  Platen,  and  above  all 
through  Donner's  excellent  ren- 
derings of  the  Greek  dramatists. 
Riickert  excelled  in  the  imitation 
and  reproduction  of  Persian,  Indian, 
and  Arabic  poetry,  and  through  him 
and  Friedrich  Bodenstedt  German 
literature  has  been  enriched  by 
many  lines  of  which  it  would  be 
difficult  to  say  whether  their  home 
was  in  Germany  or  in  the  far  East, 
so  perfectly  is  the  spirit  and  dic- 
tion reproduced.  The  well-known 
'  Weisheit  des  Brahmanen '  of 
Riickert,  and  Bodenstedt's  '  Mirza 
Schaffy '  are  examples. 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


labours  had  to  fit  in  with  the  general  plan,  to  find  a 
place  in  the  one  great  edifice. 
35.  Thirdly,  the  German  man  of  science  was  a  teacher  ;  he 

Combina- 
tion of  re-     had  to  communicate  his  ideas  to  younger  minds,  to  make 

search  and  * 

teaching,  ^e  principles  and  methods  of  research  clear,  to  guarantee, 
in  his  course  of  lectures,  something  like  completeness, 
to  give  a  comprehensive  survey ;  not  to  teach  "  une 
science  faite,"  but  to  draw  out  original  talent  in  others, 
to  encourage  co-operation  in  research,  to  portion  out  the 
common  work  to  the  talents  which  surrounded  him,  or  it 
might  be  to  direct  the  flight  of  the  aspiring  genius.1 


1  Here  the  two  main  objects  of 
academic  teaching  are  to  impart 
a  knowledge  of  the  right  method 
in  the  special  science,  and  to  give 
a  survey  of  the  whole  domain 
of  the  science.  The  two  principal 
institutions  by  wliich  these  ob- 
jects are  attained  were  first  set 
going  in  the  classical  branches  of 
study,  and  may  be  defined  by  two 
terms — the  ' '  seminary  "  and  the 
lecture  on  "  encyclopaedia. "  Both 
terms  are  taken  from  earlier  insti- 
tutions. The  seminar}"  was  origin- 
ally a  training  -  school  for  priests 
or  teachers.  Under  such  masters 
of  methodical  research  as  F.  A. 
Wolf  and  Gottfried  Hermann,  the 
institution  acquired  a  different 
character.  "The  seminaries  are 
the  real  nurseries  of  scientific 
research.  They  were  founded,  in- 
deed, with  a  different  object;  the 
first  seminaries,  the  philological 
seminaries,  which  were  started 
during  the  last  century  at  Halle 
and  Gottingen,  were  or  should  have 
been  pedagogic  seminaries  for  the 
future  masters  in  the  learned 
schools.  In  reality  they  were  — 
especially  that  of  F.  A.  Wolf — 
in  the  first  place  institutions  in 
which  the  art  of  philological  re- 
search was  taught.  This  is  even 


more  the  case  in  the  philological 
seminaries  and  societies  which 
during  the  nineteenth  century 
have  been  conducted  by  G.  Her- 
mann, Fr.  Thiersch,  Fr.  Hitschl,  and 
others :  they  were  nurseries  of 
philologists,  not  of  teachers.  And 
the  same  may  be  said  of  the  num- 
erous seminaries  which  in  modern 
times  have  grown  up  in  the  other 
sciences  within  the  philosophical 
faculty,  and  also  in  the  faculties 
of  theology  and  law  :  they  set  up 
as  their  aim — with  few  exceptions 
— the  training  for  scientific  work 
and  research,  not  the  utilisation  of 
knowledge  for  a  practical  purpose  " 
(Paulsen  in  Lexis,  'Die  deutschen 
Universitaten,'  vol.  i.  p.  74,  &c.) 
The  same  idea  was  in  the  mind  of 
Liebig  when  he  started  the  first 
chemical  laboratory  at  Giessen  (see 
supra,  p.  188,  note).  The  ency- 
clopaedic treatment  of  every  large 
subject  in  a  special  course  of  lec- 
tures arranged  for  this  purpose 
had  the  object  of  preventing  the 
different  studies  from  falling  asun- 
der or  ultimately  failing  to  unite 
in  the  realisation  of  one  great  aim. 
This  great  aim  of  all  philological 
studies,  for  instance,  was  always 
held  up  by  men  like  Wolf,  Her- 
mann, Bockh,  and  Ritschl,  among 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    GERMANY. 


215 


Lastly,  the  German  man  of  science  was  a  philosopher. 
Whatever  his  aversion  might  be  to  special  philosophical 
doctrines,  he  had  generally  come  under  the  influence  of 
some  philosophical  school,  the  teaching  of  which  he  desired 
either  to  uphold  or  to  combat.  Sooner  or  later,  con- 
sciously or  unconsciously,  he  had  to  make  clear  to  him- 
self and  to  his  disciples  the  underlying  principles  which 
he  thought  the  right  ones,  to  defend  them  against  attacks 
from  others,  or  to  modify  them,  as  progressing  research 
made  it  necessary.  If  the  historical  sciences  had  bene- 
fited most  by  the  philosophy  of  Schelling  and  Hegel, 
which  attempted  to  give  new  and  constructive  views 
on  the  intellectual  and  ethical  manifestations  of  the 
human  or  the  general  soul,  the  mathematical  and  phy- 


30. 

Combina- 

won  of 

science  and 


whose  favourite  lectures  were  those 
on  "encyclopaedia"  of  philology. 
Something  similar  existed,  and 
exists  still,  in  theology,  law,  and 
what  are  called  "  Staatstvissen- 
schaften."  All  these  terms  are 
supposed  to  embrace  a  variety  of 
studies  which  are  organically  com- 
bined in  one  whole,  forming  a  cycle. 
In  philosophy  proper  Hegel,  and 
later  Lotze,  delivered  well-known 
and  largely  attended  lectures  under 
the  title  of  Encyclopaedia.  This  is 
a  remnant  of  the  encyclopaedic  or 
organic  treatment  of  knowledge 
sketched  out  by  Bacon,  and  pro- 
posed as  a  basis  for  their  celebrated 
work  by  Diderot  and  D'Alembert 
(see  ante,  p.  35  and  note).  The 
encyclopaedia,  as  a  learned  diction- 
ary, we  have  seen,  has  since  become 
merely  a  synopsis.  How  different 
from  this  was  the  truly  encyclo- 
paedic treatment  given  by  men  like 
Bockh  can  be  seen  from  his  cor- 
respondence with  K.  0.  Miiller, 
where  he  scolds  his  younger  friend 
for  undertaking  to  write  the  article 


"  Topography  of  Athens  "  for  "  such 
a  cursed  publication  as  an  encyclo- 
paedia," whereas  he  himself  was 
regularly  lecturing  on  ' '  encyclo- 
paedia of  philology,"  in  which  he 
took  in  earnest  the  idea  of  classi- 
cal philology  as  "the  historical 
science  of  the  life  of  the  ancient 
peoples  "  (see  Curtius,  '  Alterthum 
und  Gegenwart,'  vol.  iii.  p.  138,  &c.) 
Now  although  the  exact  sciences 
when  they  became  domiciled  in  the 
German  universities  did  not  in 
general  copy  this  institution,  yet 
the  historical  and  philosophical 
survey,  giving  method  and  unity 
to  a  large  circle  of  studies,  has  been 
upheld  by  many  among  the  fore- 
most men  of  science,  especially  in 
the  medical  faculty.  Of  these  I 
only  mention  Joh.  Miiller  (see  Du 
Bois-Reymond,  '  Reden,'  vol.  ii.  pp. 
195,  279)  and  his  pupil  and  follower 
Jacob  Henle,  who  in  his  lectures 
on  anthropology  took  a  philosophi- 
cal survey  of  the  whole  subject  of 
the  medical  studies  (see  'Jacob. 
Henle'  by  Merkel,  p.  271,  &c.) 


216  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

sical  sciences  have  been  most  affected  by  the  spirit  of 
Kant's  philosophy,  which  has  ineradicably  engrained  in 
the  German  mind  the  necessity  of  a  criticism  of  the 
principles  of  knowledge.  Ever  and  anon  some  of  the 
most  brilliant  intellects  in  mathematics  and  science  have 
reverted  to  the  same  problems,  and,  on  the  whole,  they 
have  confirmed  the  position  taken  up  by  Kant  a  cen- 
tury ago. 

It  was  thus  under  the  influence  of  the  exact  methods 
of  experiment  and  calculation  taught  by  the  great  French 
school  in  the  beginning  of  the  century,  and  at  the  same 
time  through  the  philosophical  spirit  peculiar  to  German 
science,  that  in  the  middle  of  the  century  the  different 
sciences  which  deal  with  the  phenomena  of  life  and  con- 
137.  sciousness  were  remodelled.  The  great  science  of  biology, 

Biology 

grown  out     based  upon  mechanical  principles,  was  thus  created,  and 

of  science 

sophyhcom.  the  results  gained  in  it  brilliantly  applied  to  the  reorgan- 
isation of  the  medical  profession.  But  this  great  reform 
does  not  belong  exclusively  to  one  great  name ;  it  is  the 
work  of  a  long  line  of  thinkers :  nor  can  I  conceive  that 
the  exclusive  employment  of  the  methods  of  exact  re- 
search would  have  so  effectually  brought  it  about,  unaided 
by  the  philosophical,  historical,  and  critical  spirit  which 
formed  the  peculiar  characteristic  of  German  thought 
before  the  exact  methods  had  been  generally  introduced. 
And  just  because  this  reform  required  to  be  effected  from 
so  many  different  beginnings,  and  gradually  elaborated 
and  defended  before  it  became  firmly  established,  do  the 
modern  sciences  of  physiology  and  pathology  deserve  to 
be  termed  pre-eminently  German  sciences ;  for  no  other 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   GERMANY.          217 

country  possessed  the  necessary  conditions  and  extensive 
organisations,  the  habits  of  combined  study  and  patient 
co-operation,  the  large  views  and  the  high  aims,  which 
had  been  acquired  at  the  German  universities  under  the 
guidance  of  the  German  ideal  of  Wissenschaft,  and  under 
the  sway  of  the  philosophical  and  classical  spirit. 

A  great  authority,1  who  as  much  as  any  one  represents 
the  modern  as  distinguished  from  the  earlier  views  in 
biological  science,  reviewing  the  different  agencies  which 
have  brought  about  the  great  change,  speaks  thus.  He 
is  referring  to  Johannes  Mliller,  the  father  of  modern  ss. 
physiology.  "  The  modern  physiological  school,"  he  says,  Reymond 
"  with  Schwann  at  its  head,  has  drawn  the  conclusions  for 
which  Mliller  had  furnished  the  premises.  It  has  herein 
been  essentially  aided  by  three  achievements  which  Miiller 
witnessed  at  an  age  when  deeply-seated  convictions  are 
not  easily  abandoned.  I  mean,  first  of  all,  Schleiden  and 
Schwann's  discovery,  that  bodies  of  both  animals  and 
plants  are  composed  of  structures  which  develop  inde- 
pendently, though  according  to  a  common  principle.  This 
conception  dispelled  from  the  region  of  plant-life  the  idea 
of  a  governing  entelechy,  as  Miiller  conceived  it,  and 
pointed  from  afar  to  the  possibility  of  an  explanation  of 
these  processes  by  means  of  the  general  properties  of 
matter.  I  refer,  secondly,  to  the  more  intimate  know- 
ledge of  the  action  of  nerves  and  muscles,  which  began 
with  Schwann's  researches,  in  which  he  showed  how  the 
force  of  the  muscle  changes  with  its  contraction.  In- 
vestigations which  were  carried  on  with  all  the  resources 

1  See  Du  Bois-Reymond,  'Reden,'  vol.  ii.  p.  219,  &c. 


218  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

of  modern  physics  regarding  the  phenomena  of  animal 
movements,  gradually  substituted  for  the  miracles  of 
the  '  vital  forces '  a  molecular  mechanism,  complicated, 
indeed,  and  likely  to  baffle  our  efforts  for  a  long  time  to 
come,  but  intelligible,  nevertheless,  as  a  mechanism.  The 
third  achievement  to  which  I  refer  is  the  revival  among 
us  by  Helmholtz  and  Mayer  of  the  doctrine  of  the  con- 
servation of  force.  This  cleared  up  the  conception  of 
force  in  general,  and  in  particular  supplied  the  key  to  a 
knowledge  of  the  change  of  matter  in  plants  and  animals. 
By  this  an  insight  was  gained  into  the  truth  that  the 
power  with  which  we  move  our  own  limbs  (as  George 
Stephenson  did  those  of  his  locomotive)  is  nothing  more 
than  sunlight  transformed  in  the  organism  of  the  plant : 
that  the  highly  oxygenated  excrements  of  the  animal 
organism  produce  this  force  during  their  combustion,  and 
along  with  it  the  animal  warmth,  the  irvev/uia  of  the 
39.  ancients.  In  the  daylight  which  through  such  know- 
force  "aban-  ledge  penetrated  into  the  chemical  mechanism  of  plants 

doned. 

and  animals,  the  pale  spectre  of  a  vital  force  could  no 
more  be  seen.  Liebig,  indeed,  who  himself  stood  up  so 
firmly  for  the  chemical  origin  of  animal  heat  and  motive 
power,  still  retains  an  accompanying  vital  force.  But 
this  contradiction  is  probably  to  be  traced  to  the  cir- 
cumstance that  the  celebrated  chemist  came  late,  and  as 
it  were  from  outside,  to  the  study  of  the  phenomena  of 
life.  And  even  Wohler  still  believes  in  a  vital  force,  he 
who  in  his  time  did  more  than  any  one  to  disturb  the 
vitalistic  hypothesis  through  his  artificial  production  of 
urea." 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    GERMANY.          219 


It  was  a  process  of  critical  sifting  similar  to  that  which 
Kant l  applied  to  our  general  metaphysical  ideas,  which 
in  the  middle  of  the  century,  through  the  writings  of 
Berzelius  and  Liebig,  of  Schwann  and  Schleiden,  of  Henle, 
Lotze,  and  Du  Bois  -  Eeymond,  gradually  dispelled  the 
older  confused  notions,  and  firmly  established  the  mech- 
anical view  in  the  study  of  the  phenomena  of  life.  But 
as  we  are  forced  to  recognise  the  substance  of  much  of 
Kant's  philosophical  criticism  in  the  lucid  expositions 
of  Locke  and  Hume  before  him,  so  it  has  been  pointed 
out  that  the  words  of  the  eminent  French  physiologist, 
Vicq-d'Azyr,  contain  the  substance  of  the  more  modern 
ideas  on  life.2  It  required  the  co-operation  of  the  exact 


40. 

Mechanical 
view  in 
biology. 


1  The  great  influence  which  be- 
longs to  Kant  in  the  development 
of  modern  German  science  has  been 
frequently  dwelt  on.  In  more  re- 
cent times  some  of  the  first  repre- 
sentatives of  the  medical  and  bio- 
logical sciences  have  dealt  with  the 
subject,  and  the  opposition  which 
fifty  years  ago  originated  iu  the  ex- 
travagances of  some  of  Kant's  suc- 
cessors, has  given  way  to  a  renewed 
recognition  of  the  just  claims  of 
Kant.  We  may  refer  to  Du  Bois- 
Reymond,  who,  forgetting  Lotze, 
calls  Kant  the  last  philosopher  who 
took  a  part  in  the  work  of  the 
naturalist  ('Reden,1  vol.  i.  p.  33); 
to  Helmholtz,  who  in  many  passages 
of  his  popular  addresses  refers  to 
the  merits  of  Kant  ('  Vortrage  und 
Reden,'  1884,  vol.  i.  pp.  44,  368  ;  ii. 
58,  227,  234,  248,  &c.)  ;  to  Haeser 
(' Geschichte  der  Medizin,'  vol.  ii. 
p.  811).  I  will  add  to  these  the 
opinion  of  so  great  an  authority  as 
Prof.  Billroth  of  Vienna,  who,  speak- 
ing of  the  two  modern  schools  of 
medicine  in  Germany,  says  ('  Lehren 


und  Lernen  der  medicinischen  Wis- 
senschaften,'  &c.,  p.  334):  "How- 
ever great  the  degree  of  independ- 
ence may  be  which  the  two  parallel 
schools  have  attained,  they  would 
hardly  have  developed  so  rapidly 
without  the  powerful  influence 
which  came  from  France  and  in  a 
lesser  degree  from  England ;  nor  yet 
without  that  of  Immanuel  Kant, 
who  in  his  '  Autophysiology  of 
Reason  '  enlightened  German  minds 
regarding  their  own  selves,  and 
who  with  his  lively  imagination  fer- 
vently embraced  natural  science." 

2  The  remarkable  passage  re- 
ferred to  is  quoted  by  Du  Bois- 
Reymond  ('Reden,'  vol.  ii.  p.  27)  : 
"  Quelqu'  etonnantes  qu'elles  nous 
paraissent,  ces  fouctions  (viz.,  dans 
lea  corps  organises)  ne  sont-elles 
pas  des  effete  physiques  plus  ou 
moins  composes,  dont  nous  devons 
examiner  la  nature  par  tous  les 
moyens  que  nous  fournissent  1'ob- 
servation  et  I'expeYience,  et  non 
leur  supposer  des  principes  sur 
lesquels  1'esprit  se  repose,  et  croit 


220 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


spirit  of  research  with  the  critical  methods  acquired  in 
the  school  of  philosophy,  and  the  exhaustive  survey  of 
a  large  array  of  facts  acquired  through  historical  and 
classical  studies,  before  the  significance  of  this  brilliant 
apergu  became  evident ;  before  the  underlying  ideas  could 
become  useful  guides  of  research  and  progress.  "  TanUe 
molis  erat  Komanarn  condere  gentem." 

Though  the  reform  of  the  biological l  sciences,  and  their 
application  to  pathological  inquiries,  are  probably  the 
greatest  achievement  which  the  methods  of  exact  re- 
search, in  conjunction  with  the  philosophical  spirit,  can 
boast  of  in  Germany  in  the  century,  the  same  habit 


avoir  tout  fait  lorsqu'il  lui  reste 
tout  &  faire."  This  was  said  at 
the  end  of  the  last  century,  and 
fifty  years  later  Du  Bois-Reymond 
(loc.  cit.)  could  complain  that  the 
truth  contained  in  these  words  was 
not  yet  generally  admitted,  in  spite 
of  the  labours  of  Berzelius,  Schwann, 
Schleiden,  and  Lotze.  Compare 
also  A.  von  Humboldt's  own  con- 
fessions on  this  point  in  his  '  An- 
sichten  der  Natur,'  vol.  ii.  p.  309, 
&c.,  edition  of  1849. 

1  I  must  remind  the  reader  here 
that  though  I  use  the  word  biolo- 
gical as  denoting  the  more  recent 
point  of  view  from  which  all  pheno- 
mena of  the  living  world  are  being 
grouped  and  comprehended,  and 
though  the  word  seems  to  have 
been  first  used  by  a  German,  never- 
theless the  arrangement  of  studies 
at  the  German  universities  has 
hardly  yet  recognised  the  essen- 
tial unity  of  all  biological  sciences. 
They  are  unfortunately  still  divided 
between  the  philosophical  and  the 
medical  faculties.  It  is  indeed  an 
anomaly,  hardly  consistent  with 
the  philosophical  and  encyclopaedic 


character  of  German  research,  that 
palaeontology,  botany,  zoology,  and 
anthropology  should  belong  to  the 
philosophical,  whereas  anatomy, 
physiology,  and  pathology  are 
placed  in  the  medical  faculty. 
Eminent  biologists  and  anthropo- 
logists, such  as  Schleiden,  Lotze, 
Helmholtz,  and  Wuudt,  have  ac- 
cordingly belonged  to  both  facul- 
ties. To  place  biological  studies 
on  the  right  footing  would  re- 
quire a  mind  similar  to  that  of 
F.  A.  Wolf,  who  evolved  out  of 
the  vaguer  idea  of  humaniora  the 
clearer  notion  of  a  "science  of  an- 
tiquity," and  who  accordingly  was 
able  to  convert  the  training-school 
of  teachers,  the  seminary,  into  a 
nursery  of  students  of  antiquity. 
Whether  a  similar  reform  in  the 
purely  scientific  interests  of  the 
"science  of  life,"  which  is  now 
mostly  cultivated  for  the  benefit 
of  the  medical  practitioner,  can  be 
effected  in  this  age,  when  practical 
aims  are  gradually  taking  the  place 
of  scientific  ideas,  is  another  ques- 
tion. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    GERMANY.          221 

of  thought  has  shown  itself  in  other  fields  of  research, 
and  led  to  similar  innovations.  I  will  here  only  mention 
one  other  line  of  inquiry,  where  neither  exact  nor  meta- 
physical reasoning  alone  suffices,  but  where  a  combination 
of  both  is  essential.  I  mean  the  gradual  change  which,  41. 

Criticism  of 

mainly  through  the  writings  of  German  mathematicians,  vf™$£f 
has  come  over  our  fundamental  conceptions  in  the  region 
of  geometry,  algebra,  and  the  theory  of  numbers.     This 
subject   belongs  so   essentially  to   the   domain   of  pure 
thought  that  a  history  of  thought  seems  specially  called 
upon  to  take  notice  of  it.     Accordingly  I  intend  to  devote 
a  special  chapter  to  it.     At  present  it  interests  us  mainly 
because  it  is  an  outcome  of  that  peculiar  modification 
which  the  exact  or  scientific  spirit  of  thought  underwent 
when,  introduced  by  French  and  English  models,  it  came 
in  contact  with  the  philosophical  and  classical  ideal  of 
learning  in  Germany.       I  will  repeat  more  clearly  and 
concisely  what  I  mean.     The  exact  methods  of  thought, 
mainly  elaborated  in  France,  and  there  largely  applied, 
give  to  science  its  accuracy  and  definiteness.       In  spite 
of  this  accuracy  and  definiteness,  it  is  not  immediately 
clear  whether  they  will  lead  to  completeness  of  know- 
ledge,  or   whether   they  may   not   be   misapplied.      To 
guarantee  completeness,  to  make  sure  that  in  the  whole 
great  field  no  portion  has  remained  untouched  and  un- 
explored, that  love  of  detail,  that  searching  and  explor- 
ing spirit,  is  required   which   is   nursed    pre-eminently 
by  historical  and  classical  studies.     And  to  avoid   the 
abuse  of  existing  methods,  there  is  further  required  that 
critical  spirit  which  inquires  into  the  value  of  principles 


222  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

and  the  limit  of  their  usefulness.     These  three  directions 

of  thought  mark  three  tolerably  distinct  attitudes  of  the 

human  mind.       Skill  in  inventing  and  in  applying  new 

42.        and   precise   methods — the   exact  habit   or  attitude  of 

The  exact, 

cat  writhe  Bought ;  love  of  detail,  and  the  desire  for  complete  and 
SJJj^of  exhaustive  knowledge — the  historical  habit  or  attitude  of 
looght  thought;  lastly,  the  desire  to  become  fully  alive  to  the 
value  of  existing  methods  or  principles,  which  implies  a 
consciousness  of  the  limited  nature  of  one  and  every 
principle — the  critical  habit  or  attitude  of  thought.  The 
progress  of  mathematics  and  natural  science  depends  pri- 
marily on  the  first ;  classical  studies  depend  on  the  second ; 
philosophical  reasoning  mainly  on  the  last.  Each  of  the 
three  nations  which  have  led  human  progress  and  thought 
during  the  past  centuries  has  probably  been  possessed 
of  these  three  cardinal  virtues  in  equal  proportions.  For 
though  Xewton  stands  pre-eminent  in  the  first,  we  have 
Laplace  and  Gauss  and  their  numerous  followers  in  other 
countries ;  though  the  great  volume  of  classical  learning 
and  criticism  has  emanated  from  the  schools  of  "Wolf, 
Hermann,  and  Bockh,  they  themselves  point  back  to 
Bentley  and  Joseph  Scaliger ;  and  even  Kant's  unrivalled 
enterprise  was  prepared  by  Hume,  and  dates  back  to 
Descartes.  There  need,  therefore,  be  no  angry  rivalry  or 
carping  jealousy.  "We  may  point  to  the  remarkably  equal 
contributions  of  the  three  nations  to  the  general  progress 
of  thought.  But  a  very  different  and  truly  legitimate 
interest  prompts  us  to  note  how  in  the  great  performances 
of  each  nation,  in  the  literature  of  each  of  the  three  lan- 
guages, different  factors  have  been  at  work — different 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    GERMANY.          223 

agencies  have  combined  to  produce  the  effect.  In  this 
regard  the  spectacles  presented  by  French,  German,  and 
English  thought  differ.  And  there  seems  to  me  little 
doubt  that  during  a  considerable  portion  of  this  century 
the  German  universities,  grown  out  of  theological,  legal, 
and  medical  studies,  and  widening  gradually  till  they 
embraced  and  deepened  all  three  by  the  philosophical, 
the  classical,  and  the  exact  spirit  of  research,  present  that 
organisation  in  which  the  different  elements  of  thought 
are  most  equally  balanced,  through  which  modern  know- 
ledge and  the  scientific  spirit  have  been  most  widely 
and  successfully  diffused,  and  that  the  German  ideal  of  43. 

Combined  in 

Wissenschaft  embraces  at  once  the  highest  aims  of  the  the  German 

ideal  of  Wis- 

exact,    the    historical,    and    the    philosophical    lines    of  senschaft- 
thought. 

Nor  would  it  be  right  to  pass  from  the  consideration  of 
this  peculiar  feature  of  nineteenth-century  thought,  which 
is  an  outcome  of  the  German  university  system,  without 
noticing  the  moral  significance  which  this  ideal  of  Wis-  44. 

Moral  value 

senschaft  acquired,  and  which  marks  it  as  a  factor  in  of -wissen- 
progress  and  in  culture  of  much  more  importance  even 
than  the  lasting  discoveries  in  science  which  it  has  made, 
or  the  monuments  of  learning  which  it  has  reared.  It  is 
not  the  political  side  of  this  movement  which  I  refer  to, 
not  even  pre-eminently  the  educational,  though  these  are 
interesting  and  important  enough  to  demand  special  his- 
torical treatment.  What  I  should  like  to  point  to  as  the 
greatest  in  this  movement  is,  that  it  belongs  to  the  few 
and  rare  instances  in  the  history  of  mankind  when  we 
see  a  large  number  of  the  most  highly  gifted  members  of 


224  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

a  nation  following  a  purely  ideal  cause,  apart  from  the 
inducements  which  gain  or  glory  may  furnish.  The  pur- 
suit of  truth  and  the  acquisition  of  knowledge  for  its  own 
sake,  as  an  ennobling  and  worthy  occupation,  has  during 
a  large  portion  of  our  century  been  the  life-work  of  pro- 
fessors and  students  alike  in  the  German  universities. 
In  the  biographies  of  many  of  them  we  meet  with  that 
self-denial  and  elevation  of  spirit  which  is  the  true  char- 
acteristic of  every  unselfish  human  effort.  In  perusing 
these  records  of  high  aspirations,  arising  frequently  amid 
disheartening  surroundings,  these  stories  of  privations 
cheerfully  endured,  of  devotion  to  an  ideal  cause,  glow- 
ing with  all  the  fervour  of  a  religious  duty,  we  gain  a 
similar  impression  to  that  which  the  contemplation  of  the 
Classical  period  of  Greek  art  or  the  early  Eenaissance 
produces  on  our  mind. 

Once  at  least  has  science,  the  pursuit  of  pure  truth  and 
knowledge,  been  able  to  raise  a  large  portion  of  mankind 
out  of  the  lower  region  of  earthly  existence  into  an  ideal 
atmosphere,  and  to  furnish  an  additional  proof  of  the 
belief  that  there,  and  not  here  below,  lies  our  true  home. 
We  may  perhaps  have  to  admit  with  regret  that  this 
phase  is  passing  away  under  the  influence  of  the  utili- 
tarian demands  of  the  present  day ;  we  may  be  forced  to 
think  that  another — and,  we  trust,  not  a  lower — ideal  is 
held  up  before  our  eyes  for  this  and  the  coming  age. 
But  no  really  unselfish  effort  can  perish,  and  whatever  the 
duty  of  the  future  may  be,  it  will  have  to  count  among 
the  greatest  bequests  of  the  immediate  past  that  high 
and  broad  ideal  of  science  which  the  life  of  the  Ger- 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN    GERMANY. 


225 


man  universities  has  traced  in  clear  and  indestructible 
outlines.1 


1  The  testimonies  by  illustrious 
foreigners  to  the  great  work  of  the 
German  universities  are  frequent 
and  well  known,  from  the  time 
when  Mme.  de  Stael  visited  Ger- 
many, and  her  friend  Villers  wrote 
his  '  Coup-d'oeil  sur  les  Universite's 
d'Allemagne '  in  1808,  through  the 
writings  of  Cousin,  the  verdict  of 
Renan,  of  Cournot,  of  Dreyfus- 
Brisac,  and  of  the  American,  J.  M. 
Hart.  To  these  of  ten -repeated  ex- 
pressions I  will  add  that  of  the 
great  apostle  of  higher  culture  of 
our  age,  of  Matthew  Arnold,  who 
sums  up  his  interesting  report  on 
the  German  system  of  higher  edu- 
cation in  these  characteristic  words : 
"  What  I  admire  in  Germany  is, 
that  while  there,  too,  Industrialism, 
that  great  modern  power,  is  making 


at  Berlin  and  Leipzig  and  Elber- 
feld  most  successful  and  rapid  pro- 
gress, the  idea  of  Culture,  Culture 
of  the  only  true  sort,  is  in  Germany 
a  living  power  also.  Petty  towns 
have  a  university  whose  teaching 
is  famous  through  Europe ;  and 
the  King  of  Prussia  and  Count 
Bismarck  resist  the  loss  of  a  great 
savant  from  Prussia  as  they  would 
resist  a  political  check.  If  true 
culture  ever  becomes  at  last  a 
civilising  power  in  the  world,  and 
is  not  overlaid  by  fanaticism,  by 
industrialism,  or  by  frivolous  pleas- 
ure-seeking, it  will  be  to  the  faith 
and  zeal  of  this  homely  and  much- 
ridiculed  German  people  that  the 
great  result  will  be  mainly  owing  " 
('  Schools  and  Universities  on  the 
Continent,'  1868,  p.  256). 


VOL.  I. 


226 


CHAPTEE    III. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IX   ENGLAND. 


i.         THE  history  of  science  in  France  and  Germany  during 

Scientific 

°b?andsation  ^e  ^rs*  kftlf  °f  the  present  century  is  identical  with  the 
history  of  two  great  organisations,  the  Paris  Institute  and 
the  German  Universities.  It  is  to  them  that  we  owe 
nearly  all  the  great  scientific  work  in  the  two  countries : 
to  the  former  we  owe  the  foundation  of  the  modern 
methods  of  scientific  work  during  the  last  period  of  the 
eighteenth  and  the  early  years  of  the  nineteenth  cen- 
tury; to  the  latter  we  owe  pre-eminently  the  diffusion 
and  widespread  application  of  those  methods.1  "We  now 
turn  to  the  country  which,  in  advance  of  France  and  Ger- 

1  In  respect  of  this  I  cannot  suf-  j  labours  of  the  German  universities 
ficiently  recommend  M.  Maury's  i  during  this  century.  The  first  im- 
volume  on  '  L'ancienne  Academic  i  pression  we  get  from  the  perusal  of 


des  Sciences,'  which  is  as  eloquent 
a  testimonial  to  the  scientific 
labours  of  eminent  Frenchmen 
during  the  eighteenth  century  as 
the  companion  volume  on  '  L'an- 
cienne Academic  des  Inscriptions 
et  Belles  Lettres '  is  a  proof  of 
the  absence  of  philological  studies 
during  that  period.  The  recent 
publication  of  Lexis'  work,  'Die 
deutschen  Universitaten,'  is  just 


these  two  works  is  that  for  a  long 
period  France  almost  monopolised 
the  exact  sciences,  just  as  later, 
for  a  similar  period,  Germany 
almost  monopolised  classical  re- 
search, the  science  of  antiquity. 
And  yet  the  former  was  probably 
as  much  indebted  to  the  English- 
man Newton  as  the  latter  was  to 
the  Frenchman  Joseph  Scaliger  for 
the  character  each  acquired  during 


as  eloquent  a   testimonial   to   the       the  two  periods  I  refer  to. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT   IN    ENGLAND. 


227 


many,  had  produced  the  greatest  scientific  model  of  modern 
times,  a  work  which  has  probably  done  more  than  any 
other  purely  scientific  work  to  revolutionise  our  scientific 
notions — the  '  Principia  '  of  Newton.  In  the  subsequent 
history  of  the  thought  of  this  century,  the  next  chapter 
will  deal  with  the  part  that  the  Newtonian  ideas  have 
played  throughout  the  whole  period.  We  have  now  to 
turn  our  attention  to  the  state  of  science  in  Great  Britain 
during  the  period  when  Paris  academicians  and  German 
professors  combined  to  define  and  carry  the  spirit  of 
modern  scientific  thought  into  the  several  mathematical, 
physical,  and  biological  branches  of  research. 

Considering  that  the  great  scientific  institutions  of  the 
Continent — the  Paris  Institute,  the  scientific  and  medical 
schools  in  Paris,  and  the  German  universities — have  done 
so  much  for  the  furtherance  of  science  and  the  diffusion 
of  the  scientific  spirit,  it  is  natural  that  we  should  ask, 
What  have  similar  institutions   done  in  this   country  ? 
These   institutions   are.   indeed,   mostly   older   than   the  fn 
academies    and    modern    universities   of    the  Continent.  Bntam 
The  Royal  Society,  if  not  older  than  the  French  Academy, 
is  certainly  older  than  the  Paris  Academy  of  Sciences.1 


2. 

Similar  in- 


1  The  actual  dates  are  as  follows  : 
The  first  Academy  devoted  to  the 
pursuit  of  science  seems  to  have 
been  the  "Academia  Secretorum 
Naturse,"  founded  at  Naples  in  1560. 
Several  societies  devoted  to  the  cul- 
ture of  literature  and  art  existed  in 
Italy,  such  as  the  Academy  "  della 
Crusca"  (founded  at  Florence  in 
1582).  The  great  French  Academy, 
devoted  exclusively  to  the  study  of 
the  French  language,  dates  from 
1629,  and  received  its  charter  in 
1635.  The  Royal  Society,  though 


not  the  first  scheme  of  its  kind 
which  was  started  in  this  country 
— for  the  establishment  of  a  Royal 
Academy  was  discussed  as  far  back  as 
1616— actually  started  (1645)  in  the 
private  meetings  described  in  '  Dr 
Wallis's  Account  of  Some  Passages 
of  his  own  Life '  (quoted  by  Weld, 
'  Hist,  of  the  Royal  Society, '  vol.  i. 
p.  30).  These  meetings,  according  to 
him,  were  suggested  by  a  German, 
Theodore  Hank,  then  resident  in 
London.  The  members  were  "  per- 
sons inquisitive  into  natural  philos- 


228 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


The  universities  of  Oxford,  Cambridge,  Edinburgh,  Dub- 
lin, and  Glasgow l  are  older  than  most  of  the  German 
universities  which  have  done  the  great  scientific  work 
of  this  century.  So  far  as  wealth  is  concerned,  no  in- 
stitution on  the  Continent  could  compare  with  the  two 
older  English  universities,  and  the  Royal  Society  had 
in  the  beginning  of  this  century  long  emerged  from  the 
poverty  which  characterised  her  early  history  during  the 
lifetime  of  Newton.2  Let  us  look  at  the  subject  from  a 


ophy,  .  .  .  and  particularly  of  what  j 
hath  been  called  the  N  e w  Philosophy 
or  Experimental  Philosophy."     It 
formed  a  branch  at  Oxford  in  1649, 
and    received   a   royal    charter   in 
1662,  four  years  before  the  "Acad- 
emic des  Sciences  "  at  Paris — which 
had  also    previously   existed  as  a 
private  gathering  of  savants  at  the 
houses  of  Mersenne,  Montmort,  and 
Thevenot — was  formally  installed  in 
the    Bibliotheque    du    Roi.      The 
"  Accademia  del  Cimento  "  at  Flor- 
ence was  established  in  1657  ;  but 
it  only  lasted    ten    years.      Very 
irregular  were    also    the   life  and 
labours  of  the  "Academia  natune 
Curiosorum"      (later     called      A. 
Csesarea    Leopoldina),   founded   at 
Vienna  in  1652.      The  Accademia 
del  Cimento  printed  an  important 
volume  of    Transactions   in    1666. 
The   Royal    Society   published    its 
first   volume   in   1665.      The   first 
volume   of    the   'Journal   des   Sa- 
vants '  is  of  the  same  year.     Very 
complete  information  will  be  found 
on    all   foreign    Academies   in   the 
'Grande  Encyclopedic,'  art.  "Acad- 
emic." 

1  Although  the  dates  of  the  foun- 
dation of  Oxford  and  Cambridge  are 
uncertain,  they  were  certainly  more 
than  a  century — probably  two  cen- 
turies— older  than  Prague,  the  first 
German  university,  founded  by  the 
Emperor  Charles  IV.  in  1347.  The 


older  Scotch  universities  were  found- 
ed in  the  course  of  the  fifteenth 
century,  about  the  same  time  that 
Leipsic  appears  to  have  had  its 
origin  through  a  secession  from 
Prague.  The  German  universities 
—  Halle,  Gottingen  —  which  were 
the  seat  of  modern  erudition,  have 
a  much  later  date,  as  given  in  chap, 
ii.  p.  159,  above.  Edinburgh  was 
founded  at  the  end  of  the  six- 
teenth century,  and  Trinity  Col- 
lege, Dublin,  about  the  same  time. 
Ley  den,  which  exerted  a  great  in- 
fluence both  on  Scotch  and  German 
higher  education  during  the  seven- 
teenth century,  was  somewhat  older 
than  Edinburgh. 

2  It  appears  from  Weld  ('History,' 
&c.,  vol.  i.  pp.  231,  241,  246,  316,  46*2, 
473)  that  the  financial  position  of 
the  Royal  Society  was  precarious, 
and  frequently  engaged  the  serious 
attention  of  the  Council,  during 
the  whole  first  hundred  years  of  its 
existence  ;  that  as  late  as  1740  the 
whole  revenue  of  the  Society  was 
only  £232  per  annum.  An  effort 
was  then  made  to  get  in  the  large 
arrears  of  subscriptions  and  other 
contributions.  In  the  following 
year  the  income  seems  to  have 
exceeded  the  expenditure  by  £297. 
Weld  adds,  "  It  is  a  painful  task  to 
record  these  periodical  visitations 
of  poverty,  which  threatened  the 
very  existence  of  the  Royal  Society  ; 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND.          229 

different  point  of  view.    England  has  during  the  early  part        3. 
of  the  century,  in  all  but  the  purely  mathematical  sciences,  science  in 

J  '  the  early 

a  greater  array  of  scientific  names  of  the  first  order  than 
Germany,  and  nearly  as  great  an  array  as  France.  Black, 
Herschel,  Priestley,  Cavendish,  Davy,  Young,  Dalton, 
Faraday,  Eowan  Hamilton,  Brewster,  Lyell,  Charles  Bell, 
are  all  identified  with  one  or  more  novel  ideas  or  definite 
branches  of  research.1  Great  Britain  had  thus  no  lack 


there  is,  however,  a  proportionate 
amount  of  pleasure  in  witnessing 
the  triumphant  manner  in  which 


ous  difficulties,  unassisted  by  Royal 
bounty  and  labouring  alone  on  ac- 
count of  their  love  for  science " 


the  small  band  of  philosophers  ex-       (vol.  i.  p.  474). 
tricated  their  institution  from  seri- 

1  The  following  are  the  principal  dates  referring  to  the  great  discoveries 
made  in  this  country  during  the  half-century  ending  1825  : — 

1774.  Priestley  (1733-1804)  discovers  oxygen  and  a  variety  of  other 


1775.  Black  (1728-99),  Memoirs  on  latent  heat. 

1775.  Maskelyne  (1732-1811)  measures  the  Attraction  of  Mount  She- 
hallien. 

1775.  Landen  (1719-90)  expresses  the  arc  of  an  hyperbola  in  terms  of 
two  elliptic  arcs. 

1778.  Benjamin  Thompson  (Count  Rumford,  1753-1814)  first  experi- 
ments on  heat  by  friction. 

1781,  13th  March,  Sir  William  Herschel  (1738-1822)  discovers  Uranus. 

1784.  Cavendish  (1731-1810)  discovers  the  composition  of  water. 

1786-97.  Caroline  Herschel  (1750-1848)  discovers  her  eight  comets. 

1798.  Cavendish  determines  the  density  of  the  earth. 

1799.  Davy  (1768-1829),  essay  on  heat,  light,  &c. 

1800.  Nicholson  and  Carlisle  decompose  water  with  the  voltaic  pile. 

1801.  Dalton  (1766-1844),  theory  of  evaporation. 

1801.  Young  (1773-1829),  first  essay  on  the  theory  of  light  and  colour. 
1802..  Dalton,  law  of  expansion  of  gaseous  fluids. 

1802.  Playfair  (1748-1819),  'Illustrations  of  the  Huttonian  Theory.' 
1802.  Wollaston  (1766-1829),  on  Iceland  spar,  and  undulatory  theory. 
1802-3.   William  Herschel,  observations  on  nebulae  and  double  stars. 
1802-3.  Young  expounds  the  principle  of  "  Interference." 

1803-4.  Dalton  proposes  the  atomic  theory. 

1804.  Leslie  (1766-1832),  experiments  on  heat. 

1804.  Wollaston  discovers  palladium  and  other  kindred  metals. 

1806.  Davy  isolates  the  alkaline  metals. 

1807.  Young  introduces  the  word  Energy  (lect.  i.  p.  75). 

1809.  Ivory  (1765-1842),  on  the  attraction  of  ellipsoids. 

1810.  Young  (in  '  Quarterly  Review  ')  explains  the  different  refractions 

in  crystals. 
1810.  Davy  discovers  chlorine  to  be  a  simple  body. 


230  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

either  of  great  men  of  science  or  of  great  institutions, 

and  yet — in  spite  of  these — we  read  in  the  course  of 

4.        the  first  third   of    the    century    about    the    decline    of 

Alleged  de- 
cline of        science  in  England.     That  such  could  be  seriously  said 

science  in 

Bn8j*nd-  of  a  country  which  within  fifty  years  had  in  astronomy 
discovered  a  new  planet  (the  first  addition  to  the  number 
known  to  the  ancients),  had  discovered  oxygen,  latent 
heat,  and  the  decomposition  of  water,  applied  the  gal- 
vanic current  for  isolating  the  most  refractory  metals, 
laid  the  groundwork  for  the  undulatory  theory  of  light, 
established  the  atomic  theory,  put  forth  in  statics  and 
dynamics  two  of  the  most  important  modern  generalisa- 
tions,1 and  introduced  in  the  treatment  of  electric  and 

1810.  Brown  (1773-1858)  publishes  his  '  Prodromus  Florae  Novae  Hol- 

landiae,'  &c. 

1811.  Charles  Bell  (1774-1842)  asserts  the  difference  of  sensory  and 

motor  nerves. 
1813.  Brewster  (1781-1868)  begins  his  experiments  on  refraction  and 

dispersion. 
1813.  Davy  discovers  iodine. 

1813.  Wollaston  publishes  his  synoptical  scale  of  equivalents. 

1814.  Wells  (1757-1817),  essay  on  dew. 

1815.  William  Smith  (1769-1839)  publishes  his  work  on  'Strata.' 
1815.  Brewster  gives  his  law  for  determining  the  polarising  angle. 

1815.  Leslie  (1766-1832)  experiments  on  radiant  heat  and  temperature 

of  the  earth. 

1816.  Prout  (1785-1850),  Memoir  on  the  position  of  hydrogen. 

1817.  Young  (in  a  letter  to  Arago)  suggests  transverse  vibrations  of 

light. 

1819.  Eater  (1777-1835)  measures  the  length  of  the  seconds-pendulum. 
1821.  Faraday  (1781-1867)  discovers  the  rotation  of  a  coil  round  a  fixed 

magnet. 

1821.  Brown,  monographs  on  botanical  subjects. 
1821.  Sabine  (1788-1883)  experiments  on  the  dip  of  the   magnetic 

needle. 
1823.  Rowan  Hamilton  (1805-65)  presents  his  paper  on  Caustics  to 

the  Irish  Academy. 

1823.  Faraday  condenses  chlorine  and  other  gases. 

1824.  Sir  J.  Herschel  (1792-1871),  observations  of  double  stars. 

1825.  Sir  J.  Herschel,  on  the  parallax  of  fixed  stars. 


1  The  two  important  generalisa- 
tions I  refer  to  are  contained  in  : 
1.  George  Green,  'An  Essay  on 


the  Application  of  Mathematical 
Analysis  to  the  Theories  of  Elec- 
tricity and  Magnetism,'  published 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   ENGLAND. 


231 


magnetic  phenomena  novel  conceptions,  the  value  of 
which  other  fifty  years  have  hardly  sufficed  to  realise 
— is,  indeed,  an  extraordinary  fact  well  worthy  of  careful 
examination.  Certainly  the  language  in  which  Cuvier 
with  truth  congratulates  the  French  nation  on  the  pre- 
eminence which  it  has  attained  in  all  branches  of  science 
contrasts  strangely  with  the  repeated  attacks  made  in 
periodical  literature,  and  in  special  pamphlets,  on  the 
state  of  science  in  England.  And  these  not  by  persons 
ignorant  of  the  great  names  and  signal  achievements  just 
mentioned,  but  by  men  of  note,  occupying  all  but  the 
very  first  places  among  the  scientific  men  of  this  country. 

It  will  suffice  to  give  only  two  out  of  many  examples 
of  this  criticism. 

One  of  the  earliest  complaints  regarding  the  culture  of        5. 

Criticisms 

higher  mathematics  in  this  country  will  be  found  m  an  ofpiayfair. 


at  Nottingham  by  private  subscrip- 
tion in  1828.  The  term  "  potential 
function,"  to  denote  the  sum  (F) 
obtained  by  adding  together  the 
masses  of  all  the  particles  of  a 
system,  each  divided  by  its  distance 
from  a  given  point,  or  in  mathe- 

I'dm 
matical  language    Y  =  I  — ,  occurs 

there  for  the  first  time.  See 
Green's  mathematical  papers,  ed. 
Ferrers,  1871,  p.  22.  The  function 
had  before  that  time  been  used  by 
Legendre  and  Laplace,  but  Green 
was  the  first  to  give  a  general 
mathematical  theory  of  it.  His 
essay  remained  unknown  to  the 
mathematical  world,  and  the  prin- 
cipal theorems  were  independently 
published  by  Gauss  in  his  celebrated 
essay  '  Allgemeiue  Lehrsiitze  liber 
die  im  verkehrten  Verhiiltnisse  des 
Quadrats  der  Entfernung  wirken- 
den  Anziehungs-  und  Abstossungs- 
Kriifte,'  1839. 


2.  W.  Rowan  Hamilton's  memoirs 
in  the  '  Philosophical  Transactions  ' 
of  1834  and  1835,  preceded  by  his 
theory  of  systems  of  rays  in  the 
'Transactions  of  the  Royal  Irish 
Academy,'  1828.  In  these  papers 
is  contained  his  celebrated  prin- 
ciple of  varying  action,  which  is  a 
development  of  Maupertuis's  prin- 
ciple of  least — or  stationary — ac- 
tion. A  great  deal  has  been  written 
on  this  principle,  which  is  now  con- 
sidered to  be  the  most  general 
principle  of  dynamics,  as  well  for 
its  mathematical  usefulness  in  cal- 
culations (see  Kirchhoff,  '  Vorlesun- 
gen  iiber  mathematische  Physik,' 
vol.  i.  pp.  28,  29),  as  from  a  phy- 
sical point  of  view  (Helmholtz, 
in  '  Journal  fur  Mathematik,'  vol. 
100).  It  has  gained  this  import- 
ance since  the  conception  of  energy, 
or  power  to  do  work,  has  been 
placed  at  the  base  of  the  theory 
of  all  physical  processes. 


232 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


excellent  review  of  Laplace's  '  Mecanique  celeste '  by 
Playfair  in  the  ' Edinburgh  Eeview '  of  1808. l  "In  the 
list  of  the  mathematicians  and  philosophers  to  whom  the 
science  of  astronomy  for  the  last  sixty  or  seventy  years 
has  been  indebted  for  its  improvements,  hardly  a  name 
from  Great  Britain  falls  to  be  mentioned.2  .  .  .  Xothing 
prevented  the  mathematicians  of  England  from  engaging 
in  the  question  of  the  lunar  theory,  in  which  the  interests 
of  navigation  were  deeply  involved,  but  the  consciousness 
that  in  the  knowledge  of  the  higher  geometry  they  were 
not  on  a  footing  with  their  brethren  on  the  Continent. 
This  is  the  conclusion  which  unavoidably  forces  itself 
upon  us.  ...  We  will  venture  to  say  that  the  number 
of  those  in  this  island  who  can  read  the  '  Mecanique 
celeste '  with  any  tolerable  facility  is  small  indeed.  If 
we  reckon  two  or  three  in  London  and  the  military 


1  '  Edinburgh  Review, '  vol.  ii.  p. 
279,  &c.  John  Playfair  (1748-1819) 
was  a  native  of  Forfarshire,  and 
Professor  of  Mathematics,  and  later 
of  Natural  Philosophy,  at  the  Uni- 
versity of  Edinburgh.  "Playfair 
was  struck  with  the  backwardness 
of  the  English  mathematicians  in 
adopting  the  results  of  the  Conti- 
nental analysts.  While  they  boasted 
of  Newton,  they  were  unable  to 
follow  him,  and  the  mantle  of 
Newton  had  indeed  passed  over  to 
France,  where  it  rested  ultimately 
on  the  shoulders  of  Laplace.  Play- 
fair  accordingly  set  himself  to  dif- 
fuse among  his  countrymen  a  know- 
ledge of  the  progress  which  science 
had  been  making  abroad.  This  he 
did  in  a  variety  of  ways, — by  his 
articles  in  the  '  Encyclopaedia  Brit- 
annica,'  by  his  papers  in  the  Trans- 
actions of  learned  societies,  by  his 
articles  in  the  '  Edinburgh  Review,' 
and  by  his  class-teaching.  As  David 


Gregory  introduced  the  Newtonian 
philosophy,  so  Playfair  introduced 
the  Continental  methods  into  the 
studies  of  the  University  of  Edin- 
burgh "  (Sir  A.  Grant,  '  The  Story 
of  the  University  of  Edinburgh,' 
vol.  ii.  p.  302). 

2  Plavfairhereexceptshis country- 
man, Colin  Maclaurin  (1698-1746), 
' '  in  whose  time  the  teaching  of 
mathematics  at  Edinburgh  reached 
a  point  which  it  cannot  be  said  to 
have  yet  surpassed  "  (ibid. ,  vol.  ii. 
p.  299  ;  cf.  also  vol.  i.  p.  271,  where 
a  programme  published  in  1741  is 
given  of  the  mathematical  and  phy- 
sical lectures  at  Edinburgh,  which 
surpassed  probably  at  that  time 
the  teaching  of  any  other  English 
or  Continental  university).  Play- 
fair  might  have  excepted  also  Ivory 
and  the  Englishman  Landen,  both 
of  whom  were  well  known  among 
Continental  mathematicians. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


233 


schools  in  its  vicinity,  the  same  number  at  each  of  the 
two  English  universities,  and  perhaps  four  in  Scotland, 
we  shall  hardly  exceed  a  dozen,  and  yet  we  are  fully 
persuaded  that  our  reckoning  is  beyond  the  truth." 

The  other  opinion  I  am  going  to  quote  dates  from  more 
than  twenty  years  later,  and  is  contained  in  a  pamphlet  by  criticisms. 
Charles  Babbage,1  who  with  Herschel  and  Peacock  had 
done  much  to  introduce  at  the  University  of  Cambridge 
that  knowledge  of  Continental  mathematics  which,  accord- 
ing to  the  Edinburgh  Eeviewer,  was  so  much  needed.  His 
'Decline  of  the  State  of  Science  in  England'  (1830)  was 
directed  mainly  against  the  Eoyal  Society,  as  the  review 


1  Charles  Babbage  (1792-1871),  a 
native  of  Devonshire,  well  known 
all  over  Europe  through  his  calcu- 
lating machine,  was  a  very  remark- 
able and  original  man.  He  lived 
during  the  age  when  the  appli- 
cation of  machinery  to  manufac- 
tures, trades,  and  arts  produced 
the  great  reform  in  the  industrial 
system  of  this  country,  and  his 
talents,  which  might  well  have 
been  employed  in  promoting  pure 
science,  were  largely  spent  in  solv- 
ing problems  of  practical  interest. 
An  account  of  these  several  pur- 
suits and  schemes  is  given  in  his 
1  Passages  from  the  life  of  a  Philos- 
opher,' London,  1864.  Of  his 
analytical  machine  we  shall  have 
occasion  to  speak  hereafter  (see  p. 
248).  Of  the  beginnings  of  the 
new  school  of  mathematics  at  Cam- 
bridge he  gives  the  following  ac- 
count (p.  27).  Having  purchased 
for  seven  guineas  a  copy  of  Lacroix's 
'  Differential  and  Integral  Calculus,' 
he  went  to  his  public  tutor  to  ask 
the  explanation  of  one  of  his  diffi- 
culties. "  He  listened  to  my  ques- 
tion, said  ^  would  not  be  asked  in 
the  Senate  House,  and  was  of  no 


sort  of  consequence,  and  advised 
me  to  get  up  the  earlier  subjects  of 
the  university  studies."  Repeated 
experience  of  this  kind  had  the 
effect  that  he  acquired  a  distaste 
for  the  routine  studies  of  the 
place,  and  devoured  the  "papers 
of  Euler  and  other  mathemati- 
cians scattered  through  innumer- 
able volumes  of  the  Academies  of 
Petersburg,  Berlin,  and  Paris."  He 
then  perceived  "  the  superior  power 
of  the  notation  of  Leibniz."  It 
being  an  age  for  forming  societies 
for  printing  and  circulating  the 
Bible  at  Cambridge,  Babbage  con- 
ceived the  plan  of  a  society  for 
promoting  mathematical  analysis, 
and  to  parody  one  of  the  many 
advertisements  he  proposed  to  call 
it  a  society  for  promoting  "the 
Principles  of  pure  d'ism  (d  being 
Leibniz's  symbol)  in  opposition  to 
the  dot-age  (dots  being  Newton's 
notation)  of  the  university."  The 
most  important  result  of  this  move- 
ment was  the  publication  in  1816 
of  a  translation  of  Lacroix's  treatise, 
and  of  two  volumes  of  examples  in 
1820. 


234 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


of  Playfair  was  against  the  English  universities.1  "  That 
science  has  long  been  neglected  and  declining  in  England 
is  not  an  opinion  originating  with  me,  but  is  shared 
by  many,  and  has  been  expressed  by  higher  authority 
than  mine."2  The  author  then  proceeds  to  give  ex- 
tracts from  the  writings  of  Davy,  Herschel,  and  others 
on  this  subject.  "  It  cannot,"  he  says,  "  have  escaped 
the  attention  of  those  who  have  had  opportunities  of 
examining  the  state  of  science  in  other  countries,  that 


1  Some  of  the  causes  of  the  de- 
cline as  given  by  Babbage  are  in- 
teresting, the  more  so  if  we  remem- 
ber that  they  were  written  at  the 
period  which  marked  the  culmin- 
ation of  Wissenschaft  in  another 
country  (p.  10) :  "  The  pursuit 
of  science  does  not  in  England 
constitute  a  distinct  profession,  as 
it  does  in  many  other  countries. 
.  .  .  Even  men  of  sound  sense  and 
discernment  can  scarcely  find  means 
to  distinguish  between  the  posses- 
sors of  knowledge  merely  elemen- 
tary and  those  whose  acquirements 
are  of  the  highest  order.  This 
remark  applies  with  peculiar  force 
to  all  the  more  difficult  applications 
of  mathematics ;  and  the  fact  is 
calculated  to  check  the  energies  of 
those  who  only  look  to  reputation 
in  England."  In  1794  Professor 
Waring  of  Cambridge  wrote:  "I 
have  myself  written  on  most  sub- 
jects in  pure  mathematics,  and  in 
these  books  inserted  nearly  all  the 
inventions  of  the  moderns  with 
which  I  was  acquainted ;  ...  but 
I  never  could  hear  of  any  reader 
in  England,  out  of  Cambridge,  who 
took  the  pains  to  read  and  under- 
stand what  I  have  written  ; "  and 
"  he  then  proceeds  to  console  him- 
self under  this  neglect  in  England 
by  the  honour  conferred  on  him  by 
d'Alembert,  Euler,  and  Lagrange  " 


(see  Todhunter,  '  History  of  the 
Theory  of  Probability,'  p.  453). 
Babbage  remarks  (p.  13)  that  "  in 
England  the  profession  of  the  law 
is  that  which  seems  to  hold  out  the 
strongest  attraction  to  talent,"  that 
science  is  pursued  as  a  favourite 
pastime,  and  that  mathematics  "  re- 
quire such  overwhelming  attention 
that  they  can  only  be  pursued  by 
those  whose  leisure  is  undisturbed 
by  other  claims."  "  By  a  destruc- 
tive misapplication  of  talent  we  ex- 
change a  profound  philosopher  for 
but  a  tolerable  lawyer"  (p.  37). 

2  One  of  the  causes  given  by  the 
Edinburgh  Reviewer  of  1822  (vol. 
xxxvii.  p.  222)  is  the  following : 
"In  Cambridge  there  must  always 
be  a  great  number  of  men  devoted 
to  scientific  pursuits  ;  but  from  the 
want  both  of  the  facilities  and  the 
excitements  furnishedi  by  such  an 
association,  apt  to  lose  the  spirit  of 
original  investigation, — a  remark 
peculiarly  applicable  to  those  young 
men  who  yearly  distinguish  them- 
selves in  the  favourite  studies  of 
the  University,  and  who,  after  the 
laborious  course  of  discipline  by 
which  they  have  attained  the  first 
object  of  their  ambition,  are  prone, 
if  left  alone,  to  become  the  mere 
instruments  for  enabling  others  to 
pursue  the  same  course." 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN    ENGLAND. 


235 


in  England,  particularly  with  respect  to  the  more  difficult 
and  abstract  sciences,  we  are  much  below  other  nations, 
not  merely  of  equal  rank,  but  below  several  even  of 
inferior  power." 

"It  is,"  says  the  Edinburgh  Ee viewer  of  1816,1  "cer- 
tainly a  curious  problem  with  respect  to  national  genius, 
whence  it  arises  that  the  country  in  Europe  most  gener- 
ally acknowledged  to  abound  in  men  of  strong  intellect 
and  sound  judgment  should  for  the  last  seventy  or  eighty 
years  have  been  inferior  to  so  many  of  its  neighbours  in 
the  cultivation  of  that  science  which  requires  the  most 
steady  and  greatest  exertions  of  understanding,  and  that 
this  relaxation  should  immediately  follow  the  period  when 
the  greatest  of  all  mathematical  discoveries  had  been  made 
in  that  same  country." 

It  must  be  said  that  these  opinions,  expressed  as  they        7. 
were  by  men  of  the  highest  attainments,  did  not  remain  opinions  on 

English 

unchallenged  at  home  or  unnoticed  abroad.  It  will  be 
interesting  to  see  how  they  have  been  met.  Let  us  first 
hear  what  Cuvier  says  in  his  filoge  of  Sir  Joseph  Banks 
in  1 8  2 1 2  regarding  the  work  of  the  Royal  Society  during 
the  period  of  forty-one  years  of  his  presidency  :  "  During 
this  period,  so  memorable  in  the  history  of  the  human 
mind,  English  philosophers  have  taken  a  part  as  glorious 
as  that  of  any  other  nation  in  those  labours  of  the  intel- 
lect which  are  common  to  all  civilised  peoples :  they  have 
faced  the  icy  regions  of  both  poles ;  they  have  left  no 
corner  unvisited  in  the  two  oceans ;  they  have  increased 
tenfold  the  catalogue  of  the  kingdoms  of  nature ;  the 


1  'Edinburgh  Review,'  1816,  vol. 
xxvii.  p.  98. 


2  See  Cuvier, '  Eloges  historiques, 
vol.  iii.  p.  79. 


236 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


heavens  have  been  peopled  by  them  with  planets,  with 
satellites,  with  unheard-of  phenomena;  they  have  counted, 
so  to  speak,  the  stars  of  the  Milky  Way  :  if  chemistry  has 
assumed  a  new  aspect,  the  facts  which  they  have  furnished 
have  mainly  contributed  to  this  change :  inflammable  air, 
pure  air,  phlogisticated  air,  are  due  to  them ;  they  have 
discovered  how  to  decompose  water ;  new  metals  in  great 
number  are  the  outcome  of  their  analysis ;  the  nature  of 
the  fixed  alkalis  has  been  demonstrated  by  none  but 
them ;  mechanics  at  their  call  have  worked  miracles,  and 
have  placed  their  country  above  others  in  nearly  every 
line^  of  manufacture."  Another  foreigner,  Professor  Moll 
of  Utrecht,  remarked  in  his  reply  to  Mr  Babbage's 
pamphlet x :  "If  Mr  Herschel  and  some  of  his  friends 


1  The  pamphlet  was  entitled  '  On 
the  alleged  Decline  of  Science  in 
England.'  By  a  Foreigner.  Lon- 
don, 1831.  It  was  by  Dr  Moll  of 
Utrecht,  and  was  introduced  by  a 
few  lines  from  Faraday,  who,  with- 
out taking  any  side  in  the  question, 
remarked  that  "  all  must  allow  that 
it  is  an  extraordinary  circumstance 
for  English  character  to  be  at- 
tacked by  natives  and  defended  by 
foreigners."  In  the  discussion  on 
the  subject  by  this  writer,  as  also 
by  Babbage,  Herschel,  Playfair, 
Whewell — pro  and  con. — a  good 
many  points  of  importance  are 
brought  out :  some  of  them  are 
still  interesting,  others  refer  to 
defects  which  have  since  been 
remedied.  I  will  mention  a  few 
of  them.  Playfair,  in  the  '  Edin- 
burgh Review '  (vol.  xxxi.  p.  393, 
1819),  thinks  that  the  "very  ex- 
tensive dissemination  of  general 
knowledge,  which  is  so  much  the 
case  over  the  whole  of  this  king- 
dom," is  against  the  advancement 
of  the  higher  branches  of  mathe- 


matics. This  refers  probably  to 
the  absence  of  periodicals  devoted 
to  special  sciences,  such  as  the 
'  Annales  de  Chimie  et  de  Physique,' 
published  by  Arago  and  Gay-Lussac 
in  France.  In  the  absence  of  these 
special  organs,  memoirs  of  original 
value,  which  marked  an  era  in 
special  researches,  were  scattered 
in  general  literary  reviews,  as 
Young's  on  Light  and  Hieroglyphics 
in  the  '  Quarterly,'  Herschel's  and 
Airy's  in  the  '  Encyclopaedia  Metro- 
politana ' ;  and  much  good  mathe- 
matics was  buried  in  the  '  Ladies' 
Diary  '  among  poetry  of  the  "  worst 
taste"  and  "childish  scraps  of  litera- 
ture and  philosophy  "  ('Edin.  Rev.,' 
vol.  ii.  p.  282,  1808).  Another 
point  is  that  ' '  the  researches  of 
English  men  of  science  have  been 
too  much  insulated  from  each  other 
and  from  what  is  doing  in  other 
countries "  (Whewell  to  Vernon 
Harcourt,  1831  ;  see  Life  by  Tod- 
hunter,  vol.  ii.  p.  126).  The  British 
Association,  which  was  founded  very 
much  as  a  result  of  this  agitation, 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


237 


have  such  a  poor  opinion  of  the  English  scientific  journals, 
a  different  judgment  is  entertained  abroad,  as  is  well 
proved  by  the  eagerness  with  which  the  German  journal- 
ists seize  upon  every  article  issuing  from  the  presses  of 
their  British  colleagues.  The  value  which  is  set  in 
Germany  upon  the  scientific  pursuits  of  the  English, 
the  rapidity  with  which  translations  are  made  in  Germany 
of  whatever  English  philosophers  of  some  reputation  pub- 
lish, shows  abundantly  that  in  that  country  at  least,  in 
docta  Germania,  a  far  greater  value  is  set  upon  the  pro- 
ductions of  English  science  than  is  done  by  Mr  Herschel 
and  his  friends." 1 


has  remedied  this  defect;  and  special 
periodicals  exist  now  in  multitudes ; 
but  who  could  say  that  a  third 
point  has  been  sufficiently  attended 
to — viz.,  "  the  ignorance  of  foreign 
languages,  which  prevails  both  in 
England  and  in  France :  in  Eng- 
land the  number  of  those  who 
acquire  a  smattering  of  French  is 
very  small,  and  still  smaller  is  the 
number  of  those  who  know  enough 
of  German  to  read  a  book  in 
that  language  without  considerable 
trouble  "  (Dr  Moll,  loc.  cit.,  pp.  7,  8). 
A  fourth  defect  existing  at  that  time 
is  worth  mentioning,  as  we  have  long 
left  the  age  of  such  drawbacks  ;  it 
"is  the  high  price  in  England  of 
foreign  books,  in  consequence  of  an 
importation  duty."  The  paper 
duties  were  repealed  in  1861. 

1  Moll,  loc.  cit.,  p.  7.  Another  pas- 
sage is  of  interest,  as  bearing  upon 
the  difference  between  the  culture  of 
science  in  England  and  in  France : 
"  At  the  time  of  the  French  Revolu- 
tion it  so  happened,  by  the  exer- 
tions of  d'Alembert,  Clairault,  Con- 
dorcet,  and  others,  that  of  all 
sciences  mathematics  were  the 
most  fashionable.  .  .  .  With  this 
view  the  Ecole  Normale  was 


founded,  which,  though  of  short 
duration,  was  perhaps  of  more 
utility  towards  the  extension  of 
mathematical  knowledge  than  all 
the  universities  of  Europe  together. 
It  was  there  that  Laplace,  La- 
grange,  and  Monge  were  lecturers, 
and  men  like  Lacroix  among  the 
hearers.  The  study  of  classics 
having  been  in  a  great  measure 
abolished  by  the  French  Revolu- 
tion, mathematics  were  studied  in 
its  stead  ;  and  it  thus  happened 
that  a  number  of  mathematicians, 
unusually  great,  were  scattered 
over  the  soil  of  France,  and  every 
one  thought  himself  capable  de 
faire  les  x,  as  they  themselves 
called  it,  upon  any  given  subject. 
But  most  of  these  investigations 
were  all  theoretical,  and  practical 
applications  were  foregone  in  almost 
every  instance"  (p.  11).  "Mechan- 
ics in  particular  do  not  seem  acces- 
sible, according  to  the  tenets  of  the 
French  school,  to  any  man  not  well 
versed  in  sublime  analysis.  .  .  . 
Hence  it  arises  that  many  have 
acquired  a  profound  knowledge  of 
the  higher  branches  of  mathematics, 
whilst  the  more  elementary  part  of 
mathematics,  which  leads  to  the 


238 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


8.  The  answers  to  the  challenges  of   Babbage   and  the 

English  re-  .  . 

piles  to        Edinburgh    Reviewer    given   by   English   writers    them- 

Babbage,&c. 

selves  cannot  on  the  whole  be  said  to  be  very  reassur- 
ing. One  of  them  counts  the  scientific  periodicals  in 
England  and  in  France,  but  omits  to  weigh  the  merit 
of  their  respective  contributions.  Another  points  to  the 
'  Ladies'  Diary,'  in  which  many  curious  mathematical 
problems,  far  beyond  the  mere  elements  of  science,  are 
often  to  be  met  with.  A  third,  whilst  in  general  admit- 
ting the  correctness  of  Babbage's  strictures,  draws  attention 
to  the  '  Penny  Magazine  '  and  the  '  Cabinet  Cyclopaedia '  as 
counterparts  in  England  of  the  Reports  of  Cuvier  and 

9.  Berzelius  abroad.     The  true  position  was  probably  recog- 

Poundation 

of  the  Brit-   nised  by  the  founders  of  the  British  Association  for  the 

ish  Associ- 
ation.         Advancement  of  Science  about  1830,1  who  saw  that,  be- 


most  useful  applications,  is  far  less 
diffused  in  France  than  in  England" 
(p.  12).  "The  principle  of  the 
division  of  labour  [in  science]  is 
more  acted  upon  in  France  than  in 
England"  (p.  14). 

1  The  movement,  which  origi- 
nated in  the  circle  to  which  Bab- 
bage  belonged,  was  —  as  stated 
above,  p.  42 —  to  some  extent 
copied  from  the  German  Associa- 
tion founded  by  Oken  in  1822.  The 
latter  acquired  a  kind  of  European 
renown  through  the  exertions  of 
Humboldt  in  1828,  who  succeeded 
in  attracting  a  considerable  number 
of  celebrities — such  as  Gauss,  Ber- 
zelius, Oerstedt, — who  for  them- 
selves preferred  a  solitary  to  a  "  gre- 
garious "  mode  of  science.  Babbage 
was  a  guest  at  this  meeting  at  Ber- 
lin, and  gave  an  account  of  it  in  an 
appendix  to  the  'Decline  of  Science.' 
A  good  account  of  the  character  I 
and  gradually  declining  influence  | 
of  these  German  meetings  will  be 
found  in  Bruhns'  '  Life  of  Hum-  , 


boldt'  (vol.  ii.  p.  127,  &c.,  transla- 
tion). They  "  degenerated  after  the 
usual  German  fashion  into  the  un- 
intellectual  form  of  feasting."  The 
British  Association  for  the  Advance- 
ment of  Science,  founded  shortly 
afterwards  on  the  27th  September 
1831  at  York,  was  the  immediate 
outcome  of  a  suggestion  thrown 
out  by  Brewster  at  the  end  of  a 
review  in  the  '  Quarterly '  of  Bab- 
bage's 'Decline  of  Science.'  He 
fully  endorsed  the  latter's  opinion, 
and  was  even  more  severe  upon  the 
universities,  maintaining  "  that  the 
great  inventions  and  discoveries 
which  have  been  made  in  England 
during  the  last  century  have  been 
made  without  the  precincts  of  our 
universities.  In  proof  of  this  we 
have  only  to  recall  the  labours  of 
Bradley,  Dollond,  Priestley,  Caven- 
dish, Maskelyne,  Rumford,  Watt, 
Wollaston,  Young,  Davy,  and  Che- 
venix ;  and  among  the  living  to 
mention  the  names  of  Dalton,  Ivor}7, 
Brown,  Hatchett,  Pond,  Herschel, 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND.          239 

sides  a  number  of  separate  societies,  "  concentration  was 
needed  in  one  association  in  order  to  give  more  systematic 
direction  to  scientific  inquiry,  and  that  the  first  thing 
needed  would  be  to  procure  reports  on  the  state  and  the 
desiderata  of  the  several  branches  of  science."  Babbage, 
at  the  Oxford  meeting  in  1832,  "expressed  the  general 
feeling  that  meetings  should  be  held  in  places  likely  to 
bring  science  into  contact  with  that  practical  knowledge 
on  which  the  wealth  of  the  country  depends."  There  is 
also  no  doubt  that  in  the  course  of  half  a  century  the 
British  Association  has  done  a  very  extensive  service 
to  science  in  the  direction  of  supplying  the  wants  which 
its  early  founders  clearly  defined,  and  in  bringing  about 
that  concerted  action  and  scientific  co-operation  which  so 
highly  distinguishes  the  great  academies  and  universities  of 
France  and  Germany.1  It  has  done  so  without  altogether 
destroying  that  peculiar  feature  which  characterises  not  10. 
only  the  scientific  but  all  the  forms  of  the  higher  mental  istics  of 

higher  men- 

work  of  this  country.  In  no  country  has  the  voice  of 
public  criticism  been  so  free  to  unveil  the  shortcomings 
which  attach  to  all — even  the  highest — human  effort.  In 
England  there  has  existed  for  a  long  time  the  habit  of 
promoting  advance  in  every  department  by  the  cultiva- 


Babbage,  Henry,  Barlow,  South, 
Faraday,  Murdoch,  and  Christie ; 
nor  need  we  have  any  hesitation 
in  adding  that  within  the  last  fif- 
teen years  not  a  single  discovery  or 
invention  of  prominent  interest  has 
been  made  in  our  colleges,  and  that 
there  is  not  one  man  in  all  the  eight 
universities  of  Great  Britain  who  is 
at  present  known  to  be  engaged  in 
any  train  of  original  research" 
('Quarterly  Review,'  vol.  xliii.  p. 
327,  1830).  He  then  suggests  "an 


association  of  our  nobility,  clergy, 
gentry,  and  philosophers  "  (p.  342). 
1  The  British  Association  has  from 
the  beginning  had  two  features  which 
did  not  exist  in  the  German  so- 
ciety —  first,  the  Reports  on  the 
position  of  various  branches  of  sci- 
ence, delivered  by  specialists  of  the 
highest  ability  ;  and,  secondly,  the 
Committees,  which  undertake  to 
do  special  work  requiring  concerted 
action. 


240  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

tion  of  party  spirit,  party  criticism,  and  party  shibbo- 
leths, as  the  easiest  method  of  enlisting  popular  favour l 
and  individual  interest ;  for  here  there  exists  no  central 
authority  which  can  create  powerful  organisations  or  dis- 
burse public  means  without  the  distinctly  and  repeatedly 
expressed  support  of  a  large  section  of  the  people.  But 
all  this  must  not  induce  us,  in  our  historical  survey, 
to  dwell  on  the  defects  rather  than  on  the  excellence  of 
the  British  contributions  to  the  growth  and  the  diffusion 
of  science.  Brilliant  is  undoubtedly  the  array  of  British 
names  which  have  during  the  first  half  of  this  century 
become  immortal  by  scientific  labours,  and  it  would  be 
narrow-minded  simply  to  emphasise  the  fact  that  they  have 
not  done  so  by  the  same  means  and  through  the  same 
organisations  as  the  Continental  nations  have  established 
and  perfected.  For  we  must  not  forget  that  these  even, 
with  all  their  rightly  extolled  universality  and  breadth 
of  spirit,  have  sometimes  failed  to  recognise  merit  or  to 
11.  encourage  genius.  In  spite  of  the  impartial  dealings  of 

Academies 

tities  not61"   ^e  Institute,  on  which  Cuvier  congratulates  the  French 
partua.im"    People,  there   are   several  instances  in  which  contribu- 
tions of  the  first  order  lay  unnoticed  for  many  years. 


1  Referring  to  the  British  Asso- 
ciation itself,  Charles  Lyell  wrote 
in  1838,  after  the  Newcastle  meet- 
ing, to  Charles  Darwin  :  "  Do  not 
let  any  papers,  whether  of  saints 
or  sinners,  induce  you  to  join  in 
running  down  the  British  Associa- 
tion. I  do  not  mean  to  insinuate 
that  you  ever  did  so,  but  I  have 
myself  often  seen  its  faults  in  a 
strong  light,  and  am  aware  of  what 
may  be  urged  against  philosophers 
turning  public  orators,  &c.  But  I 
am  convinced,  although  it  is  not 
the  way  I  love  to  spend  my  own 


time,  that  in  this  country  no  im- 
portance is  attached  to  any  body 
of  men  who  do  not  make  occasional 
demonstrations  of  their  strength  in 
public  meetings.  It  is  a  country 
where,  as  Tom  Moore  justly  com- 
plained, a  most  exaggerated  im- 
portance is  attached  to  the  faculty 
of  thinking  on  your  legs,  and  where, 
as  Dan  O'Connell  well  knows,  no- 
thing is  to  be  got  in  the  way  of  hom- 
age or  influence,  or  even  a  fair  share 
of  power,  without  agitation  "  ('  Life, 
Letters,  and  Journals  of  Sir  C.  Lyell,' 
London,  1881,  vol.  ii.  p.  45,  &c.) 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN  ENGLAND. 


241 


Fourier's  great  work  on  the  theory  of  heat,  which  for  the       12. 

Fourier. ; 

first  time  propounded  a  universal  method  applicable  to 
the  mathematical  treatment  of  almost  every  physical 
problem,  inasmuch  as  it,  so  to  speak,  follows  nature  into 
the  marvellous  composition  of  the  many  movements  out 
of  which  all  her  phenomena  are  compounded,  lay  buried 
for  fourteen  years  in  the  archives  of  the  Institute.  That 
great  authority  had  failed  to  recognise  its  paramount 
importance.1  Fresnel's  first  memoir,  which  established  is. 

Fresnel. 

on  a  firm  mathematical  basis  the  undulatory  theory  of 
light,  was  for  years  left  unpublished,  whilst  the  whole 
scientific  world  was  anxiously  expecting  the  results  of 
his  inquiries.2  In  Germany  we  have  examples  of  similar 


1  Jean  Bapt.  Jos.  Fourier  (1768- 
1830),  of  humble  origin,  in  his 
celebrated  "Theorie  analytique  de 
la  Chaleur'  (Paris,  1822),  and  in 
previous  memoirs,  carried  further 
the  mathematical  treatment  of  phy- 
sical phenomena  and  introduced 
wider  conceptions  of  mathematical 
quantities  and  their  dependence — 
i.e.,  of  a  mathematical  "function." 
His  investigations  have  led  to  far- 
reaching  applications  in  physical 
science  (Ohm  and  Lord  Kelvin), 
and  to  profound  mathematical  theo- 
ries (Dirichlet,  Riemann,  &c.)  The 
so-called  "  Fourier"  series  has  thus 
a  great  applied  as  well  as  theoreti- 
cal interest.  Fourier's  first  memoir 
was  presented  to  the  Institute  in 

1807  ;  an  extract  was  published  in 

1808  ;   a  second  memoir  was  pre- 
sented in   1811  and  crowned,  but 
was  not  printed  till  1824,  two  years 
after  the  great  work  itself  had  ap- 
peared.   On  the  physical  importance 
of    Fourier's    analysis    see    Helm- 
holtz,  '  Vortriige  und  Reden,'  vol.  i. 
p.    101,    &c.  ;    Sir    W.    Thomson, 
Mathematical  and  Physical  Papers, 
passim,  but  especially  vol.  ii.  p.  41, 

VOL.  I. 


&c.  On  the  purely  mathematical 
interest  that  attaches  to  the  Fou- 
rier series  see  especially  Riemann, 
'  Mathematische  Werke,'  p.  218, 
&c.  A  very  concise  summary  of 
the  history  of  the  series  is  also 
given  by  George  A.  Gibson  in  the 
'  Proceedings  of  the  Edinburgh 
Mathematical  Society,'  vols.  xi.  and 
xii.  We  shall  revert  to  this  subject 
in  a  subsequent  chapter. 

2  Augustin  Fresnel  (1788-1827) 
divides  with  Thomas  Young  the 
merit  of  having  established  the 
undulatory  theory  of  light  on  a 
firm  basis.  His  first  memoir  on 
Diffraction  of  Light  was  presented 
to  the  Academy  in  1815,  a  more 
extensive  paper  in  1818  ;  this  was 
crowned  in  1819,  but  not  printed 
till  1826.  Other  papers  of  his 
were  mislaid  or  lost.  The  delay 
in  bringing  before  the  world  these 
important  discoveries  has  been  at- 
tributed to  the  opposition  of  La- 
place and  his  party  in  the  Institute, 
which  even  the  influence  of  Arago 
could  not  overcome.  See  what  Sir 
John  Herschel  says  in  1827,  refer- 
ring to  Fresnel's  memoir  of  1821  on 

Q 


242 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


14. 

Pliicker. 


discouragement  and  neglect  being  thrown  in  the  way  of 
the  growth  of  new  ideas.  Pliicker  of  Bonn  laboured  for 
many  years  on  the  union  of  the  geometrical  and  analytical 
methods  in  the  treatment  of  geometry ;  but  he  found  so 
little  appreciation  that  he  abandoned  his  investigations, 
and  only  resumed  them  when  in  after-years  a  similar  line 
of  thought  was  independently  developed  in  England.1 


Transverse  Vibrations,  which  the 
Academy  had  recommended  to  be 
printed  :  "We  are  sorry  to  observe 
that  this  recommendation  has  not 
yet  been  acted  upon,  and  that  this 
important  memoir,  to  the  regret 
and  disappointment  of  men  of  sci- 
ence throughout  Europe,  remains 
yet  unpublished  "  ('  Ency.  Metrop.,' 
article  "Light").  A  full  account 
of  the  opposition  and  difficulties 
which  both  Young  and  Fresnel 
had  to  encounter  will  be  found  in 
Whewell's  '  History  of  the  Induc- 
tive Sciences,'  vol.  ii.  In  earlier 
times  Reaumur  seems  to  have  ex- 
ercised a  similar  tyranny  in  the 
Academy  of  Sciences :  see  Maury, 
'  Les  Academies  d'autrefois,'  vol.  i. 
pp.  280, 123;  also  Huxley,  'Critiques 
and  Addresses,'  1890,  p.  112,  &c. 

1  Julius  Pliicker  (1801-68),  pro-- 
fessor  at  Bonn,  equally  known  in 
England  by  his  scientific  co-opera- 
tion with  Faraday  and  by  that 
with  Cayley  and  Salmon,  worked 
both  in  physics  and  geometry  on 
independent  lines.  In  the  latter 
especially  he  brought  about  that 
union  of  purely  geometrical  and 
algebraic  methods  which  has  be- 
come so  fruitful  in  the  development 
of  modern  geometry  and  modern 
algebra.  He  had  two  periods  of 
original  geometrical  work.  The 
first  began  in  1826  (the  year  of 
the  revival  of  mathematics  in  Ger- 
many), and  closed  in  1846.  His 
mathematical  researches  were  little 
noticed  in  his  own  country,  where- 
as in  France,  and  still  more  in 


England,  his  name  was  well  known. 
After  having  published  in  1846  a 
'  System  of  Geometry,'  which  con- 
tained his  former  results  iij  a  more 
methodical  form,  he  dropped  his 
mathematical  researches  for  twenty 
years,  during  which  time  he  devoted 
himself  to  physical  investigations  of 
great  originality.  By  these,  if  he 
had  not  been  a  personal  friend,  he 
might  almost  have  been  called  a 
rival  of  Faraday  (G.  Chrystal  in 
'Ency.  Brit.')  During  a  visit  to 
England  in  1864  he  was  agree- 
ably surprised  to  meet  with  ap- 
preciative interest  from  English 
geometricians,  who  had  independ- 
ently worked  on  the  same  lines  as 
he  had  done  twenty  years  earlier. 
He  was  thus  induced  to  resume  his 
favourite  studies,  and  to  develop  an 
idea  which  had  already  been  expres- 
sed in  his  last-named  work  of  1846. 
This  led  to  a  new  fundamental  con- 
ception of  geometrical  forms,  in 
which  not  the  point  but  the  line 
is  the  element  of  space.  He  was 
not  spared  to  complete  this  line- 
geometry,  but  after  his  death  his 
pupils  found  sufficient  material  to 
put  his  researches  into  a  systematic 
form  under  the  title,  'Neue  Geo- 
metric des  Raumes,  gegriindet  auf 
die  Betrachtung  der  geraden  Linie 
als  Raumelement'  (Leipzig,  1868 
and  1869).  See  Clebsch  on  Julius 
Pliicker,  Gottingen,  1872.  A  very 
appreciative  notice  of  Pliicker,  by 
George  Chrystal,  will  be  found  in 
the  9th  edition  of  the  '  Encyclopae- 
dia Britannica. ' 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


243 


Grassmann,  in  his  '  Ausdehnungslehre,'  published  in  1844, 
is  now  generally  admitted  to  have  originated  quite  a  novel 
way  of  considering  geometrical  relations.1  It  took  twenty 
years,  however,  before  he  succeeded  in  attracting  any  at- 
tention, and  his  great  work,  of  which  the  first  edition  had 
been  sold  as  waste-paper,  was  later  on  reprinted  in  its 
original  form — mathematicians  having  now  begun  to  study 
and  recognise  its  intrinsic  value.  Such  cases  of  neglect 
have  undoubtedly  been  much  more  frequent  in  England, 
where  even  at  the  present  day  no  central  organisation 
exists  which  annually  collects  and  arranges  the  scattered 
labours  of  individual  workmen,  and  where  that  historical 
and  encyclopaedic  spirit  is  wanting  which  does  its  utmost 
to  guarantee  completeness  and  thoroughness  of  search 
and  of  research.  Men  of  the  greatest  eminence,  pioneers 


15. 
Grassmann. 


16. 

Central  or- 
ganisation 
wanting  in] 
England. 


1  Hermann  Grassmann  (1809-77) 
was  boru,  lived,  and  died  at  Stettin. 
He  did  not  succeed  till  late  in  life, 
and  fully  thirty  years  after  he  had 
published  his  original  investigations 
in  geometry,  in  gaining  for  these  the 
recognition  and  appreciation  which 
they  deserved.  Neither  he  nor  even 
Jacob  Steiner  at  Berlin  attained  to 
positions  worthy  of  their  ability  ; 
the  latter,  in  spite  of  his  connec- 
tion with  other  great  mathemati- 
cians, never  filled  the  chair  of  an 
ordinary  professorship,  whilst  the 
former  never  entered  the  sphere  of 
university  teaching  at  all.  The 
'  Ausdehnungslehre,'  as  a  new 
branch  of  mathematics,  appeared 
in  1844.  It  is  a  science  of  pure 
extension,  the  application  of  which 
to  empirical  space  is  geometry. 
Similar  investigations,  in  which 
space  of  three  dimensions  is  con- 
sidered to  be  merely  a  particular  case 
of  pure  extension  of  any  number  of 
dimensions,  which  are  not  neces- 
sarily determined  by  the  same  pro- 


perties as  our  empirical  space,  have 
become  familiar  since  the  publica- 
tion of  Riemann's  celebrated  disser- 
tation of  1854  (published  in  1867), 
and  since  Helmholtz  was  led  to 
similar  investigations  by  consider- 
ing the  different  dimensions  or 
manifoldnesses  of  our  sense  per- 
ceptions (see  his  'Vortrage  und 
Reden,'  in  many  passages).  Grass- 
mann, who  at  the  end  of  his  life 
witnessed  the  growing  appreciation 
of  his  ideas,  had  filled  up  the  in- 
terval with  entirely  different  studies, 
the  translation  of  the  '  Rig- Veda ' 
(Leipzig,  1876-77),  and  the  compo- 
sition of  a  dictionary  to  the  same 
(1872-75).  He  seems  to  have  been 
the  only  mathematician,  besides 
Thomas  Young,  who  combined  the 
ability  for  exact  mathematico- 
physical  and  for  philological  studies. 
Both  can  complain  of  having  been 
very  insufficiently  appreciated  by 
their  contemporaries.  See  Victor 
Schlegel,  '  Hermann  Grassmann,' 
Leipzig,  1878. 


244 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


Thomas 
Young. 


in  their  line  of  thought  and  discovery,  have  to  the  present 
day  remained  popularly  unknown  to  their  countrymen, 
who  have  not  only  neglected  but  reviled  them,  allowing 
their  great  discoveries  to  be  taken  up  as  their  own  by 
foreigners.  Such  was  Dr  Thomas  Young,  whom  many 
educated  persons  at  the  present  day  cannot  distinguish 
from  the  author  of  '  Night  Thoughts.' l  The  great  founder 


1  Thomas  Young  (1773-1829),  a 
native  of  Somersetshire,  attained 
equal  eminence  by  his  discoveries 
in  connection  with  the  undulatory 
theory  of  light,  in  which  he  was 
the  first  to  assert  the  principle  of 
interference  and  that  of  transverse 
vibrations,  and  by  his  discovery 
of  the  key  to  the  system  of  hiero- 
glyphics. Of  his  discoveries  and 
suggestions  some  were  published  in 
anonymous  review  articles  (so  es- 
pecially his  hieroglyphical  papers) ; 
some  in  his  Lectures  on  Natural 
Philosophy,  delivered  early  in  the 
century  at  the  Royal  Institution, 
and  published  1807  ;  some  in  the 
'  Transactions  of  the  Royal  Society ' 
(from  1800  onwards) ;  and  some  in 
various  collective  works,  especially 
the '  Encyclopaedia  Britannica.'  The 
remarkable  fact  that  Young,  of 
whom  Helmholtz  says  ('  Vortrage 
und  Reden,'  vol.  i.  p.  279)  that  he 
came  a  generation  too  soon,  re- 
mained scientifically  unrecognised 
and  popularly  almost  unknown  to 
his  countrymen,  has  been  explained 
by  his  unfortunate  manner  of  ex- 
pression and  the  peculiar  channels 
through  which  his  labours  were  an- 
nounced to  the  world.  His  fre- 
quently unintelligible  style,  his  ob- 
scure and  inelegant  mathematics, 
the  habitual  incognito  which  he  pre- 
served, his  modesty  in  replying  to 
attacks,  and  his  general  want  of 
method  in  enunciating  his  ideas,  con- 
trast very  markedly  with  the  writ- 
ings of  some  of  his  rivals,  especially 


in  France,  where  the  qualities  of 
style,  method,  and  elegance  were 
highly  developed,  and  where  recog- 
nised organs  existed  for  the  pub- 
lication of  works  of  genius.  The 
historian  of  thought,  however,  must 
not  omit  to  state  that  several  great 
names  contributed,  by  the  author- 
ity they  commanded,  to  oppose 
Young's  claims  to  originality  and 
renown.  Lord  Brougham,  shielded 
by  the  powerful  anonymity  of 
the '  Edinburgh  Review,'  and  osten- 
tatiously parading  the  authority  of 
Xewton,  submitted  the  views  of 
Young  to  a  ruthless  and  unfair 
criticism,  the  popular  influence  of 
which  Young  probably  never  over- 
came. The  great  authority  on  op- 
tics, Brewster,  who  has  enriched 
that  science  by  such  a  number  of 
experiments  and  observations  of 
the  first  importance,  never  really 
adopted  the  theories  of  Young  and 
Fresnel.  In  the  other  great  branch 
of  research  with  which  Young's 
name  is  now  indissolubly  connect- 
ed, in  the  science  of  hieroglyphics, 
the  authority  of  Bunsen  decided 
against  Young  and  for  the  French- 
man Champollion.  But  this  de- 
cision, which  did  so  much  to  ob- 
scure the  merits  of  Young,  was 
founded  on  an  insufficient  know- 
ledge of  the  dates  of  Young's  pub- 
lications. Since  these  were  collect- 
ed by  Leitch  in  the  third  volume 
of  the  '  Miscellaneous  Works '  of  Dr 
Young  (London,  1855),  the  chrono- 
logy of  his  discoveries,  which  begin 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


245 


of  modern  chemistry,  who  next  to  Lavoisier  did  more 
than  any  one  else  to  introduce  into  this  science  mathe- 
matical ideas,  John  Dalton,  grew  old  and  infirm  before  is. 

Dalton. 

his  countrymen  sufficiently  recognised  and  honoured  him. 
Deprived  of  all  but  the  very  meanest  apparatus  for  the 
proofs  of  his  theories,  and  yet  able  to  do  what  he  did, 
what  might  not  such  a  genius  have  accomplished  if  he 
had  possessed  the  means  of  a  Gay-Lussac  or  a  Regnault  ? l 


in  1814,  has  been  well  established. 
See  Benf ey, '  Geschichte  der  Sprach- 
wissenschaft '  (Miinchen,  1869,  p. 
729).  Bunsen  pronounced  his  ver- 
dict in  his  well  -  known  work, 
*  Egypt's  Place  in  Universal  His- 
tory,' published  in  1845-57.  On  the 
whole,  the  words  of  Peacock,  '  Life 
of  Dr  Young'  (London,  1855),  p. 
472,  are  still  correct :  "  His  scien- 
tific works  were  rarely  read  and 
never  appreciated  by  his  contem- 
poraries, and  even  now  are  neither 
sufficiently  known  nor  adequately 
valued  ;  whilst  if  justice  was  award- 
ed more  promptly  and  in  more  lib- 
eral measure  by  his  own  countrymen 
to  his  hieroglyphical  labours,  these 
also  were  singularly  unfortunate,  as 
far  as  concerned  the  general  diffu- 
sion of  his  fame,  by  coming  into 
collision  with  adverse  claims,  which 
were  most  unfairly  and  unscrupu- 
lously urged  in  his  own  age,  and 
not  much  less  so  by  some  distin- 
guished writers  in  very  recent 
times." 

1  John  Dalton  (1766-1844),  a 
native  of  Cumberland,  spent  the 
greater  part  of  his  life  in  teaching 
elementary  mathematics  at  Man- 
chester, first  at  a  college  and  then 
privately.  In  1801  he  propounded 
the  law  known  under  the  joint  name 
of  Dalton  and  Gay-Lussac  (who 
stated  it  six  months  later).  In  the 
jears  immediately  following  he  ela- 
borated his  atomic  theory,  which 
was  to  account  for  the  existence  of 


those  definite  quantitative  relations 
between  the  chemical  constituents 
of  bodies  known  already  to  Richter. 
It  was  published  in  1805.  But  the 
man  who  did  most  to  make  known 
to  chemists  the  ideas  of  Dalton  was 
Thomas  Thomson  (1773-1852),  Pro- 
fessor of  Chemistry  at  Glasgow,  who 
in  1807,  in  the  3rd  edition  of  his 
'  System  of  Chemistry,'  gave  an  ac- 
count of  the  atomic  theory  based 
upon  communications  of  Dalton. 
Two  memoirs  published  in  the 
'  Philosophical  Transactions '  of 
1808 — one  by  Thomson  on  "  Oxalic 
Acid,"  and  one  by  Wollaston  on 
"  Super- Acid  and  Sub-Acid  Salts  " 
— pointed  to  the  great  importance 
of  the  atomic  theory,  which  (Wol- 
laston prophetically  added)  would 
not  stop  short  with  the  determin- 
ation of  the  relative  weights  of 
elementary  atoms,  but  would  have 
to  be  completed  by  a  geometrical 
conception  of  the  arrangement  of 
the  elementary  particles  in  all  the 
three  dimensions  of  solid  exten- 
sion. The  real  merit  of  having  ex- 
perimentally proved  the  theory  of 
Dalton  belongs  to  Berzelius,  whereas 
Sir  Humphry  Davy  opposed  it  for 
many  years  after  it  had  been  ac- 
cepted abroad.  Dalton  himself  by 
no  means  followed  the  development 
which  his  ideas  underwent  at  the 
hands  of  others.  For  example,  he 
opposed  Gay-Lussac's  law  of  vol- 
umes. He  was  on  the  whole  more 
successful  in  working  out  his  own 


246 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


19. 

Faraday. 


20. 
Green. 


Faraday,  instead  of  being  backed  by  a  wealthy  Academy 
and  ample  assistance,  had  during  all  the  years  when  his 
great  discoveries  were  being  made,  to  keep  alive,  with  an 
income  scarcely  exceeding  a  hundred  pounds  a-year,  an 
institution  which  but  for  him  the  memory  even  of  such 
names  as  Eumford,  Young,  and  Davy  would  not  have 
sufficed  to  preserve  from  utter  ruin  and  collapse.1  The 
author  of  one  of  the  most  suggestive  treatises  in  the 
application  of  mathematics  to  physical  phenomena, 
George  Green,  published  it  in  1828  at  Nottingham  by 
private  subscription.  Seventeen  years  later,  "William 
Thomson  (Lord  Kelvin)  tried  in  vain  to  procure  a  copy 


ideas  than  in  comprehending  those 
of  others  who,  like  Berzelius,  Mits- 
cherlich,  Laplace.  Liebig,  and  many 
later,  contributed  to  the  confirma- 
tion of  the  atomic  theory.  A  good 
account  of  this  is  given  in  Henry's 
1  Life  of  Dalton '  (1854)  and  "in 
Kopp's  '  Entwickelung  der  Chemie 
in  der  neueren  Zeit'  (Miinchen, 
1873). 

1  Michael  Faraday  (1791-1867), 
though  not  a  mathematician,  intro- 
duced into  the  science  of  electricity 
those  ideas  which  have  since  been 
developed  into  a  mathematical  the- 
ory approaching  in  completeness  the 
mathematics  of  the  undulatory  the- 
ory of  light.  What  the  atomic  the- 
ory has  done  for  chemistry,  Fara- 
day's lines  of  force  are  now  doing  for 
electrical  and  magnetic  phenomena. 
Dalton,  though  unacquainted  with 
the  higher  mathematics  of  the 
French  school,  had  essentially  a 
mathematical  or  arithmetical  mind. 
Faraday's  peculiar  ideas  on  the 
nature  of  electrical  and  magnetic 
action,  though  supported  by  an  ex- 
perimental knowledge  many  times 
surpassing  in  volume  and  accuracy 
that  of  Dalton,  did  not  find  much 
appreciation  among  his  contem- 


poraries. They  were  much  more 
interested  in  his  experimental  re- 
searches than  in  his  theories.  In 
France  an d)Italy  Faraday's  eminence 
was  recognised  early.  Already  in 
1823  he  was  elected  member  of  the 
Academies  of  Paris  and  Florence, 
almost  before  any  society  at  home 
had  received  him.  "  The  circum- 
stances under  which  Faraday's  work 
was  done  were  those  of  penury. 
During  a  great  part  of  the  twenty- 
six  years  the  Royal  Institution  was 
kept  alive  by  the  lectures  which 
Faraday  gave  for  it.  'We  were 
living,'  as  he  once  said  to  the 
managers,  'on  the  parings  of  our 
own  skin.'  He  noted  even  the 
expenditure  of  the  farthings  in 
research  and  apparatus.  He  had 
no  grant  from  the  Royal  Society, 
and  throughout  almost  the  whole 
of  his  time  the  fixed  income  which 
the  Institution  could  afford  to  give 
him  was  £100  a-year,  to  which  the 
Fullerian  professorship  added  nearly 
£100  more  "  (Bence  Jones. '  Life  and 
Letters  of  Faraday,'  London,  1870, 
vol.  ii.  p.  344).  See  also  Bence 
Jones,  '  The  Roval  Institution,,' 
p.  311. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


247 


of  this  document,  of  which  he  knew  by  a  reference  in 
another  work.  At  last  he  got  possession  of  a  copy  which 
had  probably  during  all  this  time  been  buried  in  the 
library  of  a  prominent  mathematical  tutor  at  Cam- 
bridge, with  whom  he  had  been  in  frequent  intercourse. 
Thomson  then  took  it  with  him  to  Paris,  where  Sturm 
and  Liouville  at  once  recognised  its  merits.  He  then 
published  it  in  '  Crelle's  Journal,'  where  it  has  ever 
since  been  referred  to  as  a  fundamental  essay  on  the 
so-called  potential  theory.1  One  of  the  most  original 
thinkers  on  mathematics,  who  introduced  a  novel  prin- 
ciple into  algebraical  science,  George  Boole,  never  at-  21. 

Boole. 

tained  to  a  higher  position  than  that  of  teacher  at  a 
remote  Irish  provincial  College.2  But  perhaps  the  most 
signal  example  of  the  want  of  support  which  the 


1  See  note  1  to  p.  231  ;  also  Sir 
William  Thomson,  reprint  of  papers 
on    "  Electrostatics    and    Magnet- 
ism," 2nd  ed.,  London,  1884,  p.  2, 
note  ;  p.  126,  note. 

2  George  Boole  (1815-64),  a  native 
of  Lincolnshire,  was  one  of  the  few 
gi-eat  and  original  mathematicians 
who,  like  Leibniz  and  Grassmann, 
and  to  some  extent  Gauss,  looked 
at  the  logical  as  well  as  the  purely 
arithmetical   side  of  the   language 
of  symbols.     Though  his  treatises 
on  '  Differential  Equations '  (1859) 
and  on  'Finite  Differences'  (1860) 
have  become  well-known  text-books, 
and  his  'Laws  of  Thought'  (1854), 
in  which  he  examined  the  found- 
ations of  the  mathematical  theories 
of  logic  and  probabilities,  remains  a 
unique  work,  his  principal  services 
to   science  lie  in  the   direction  of 
the  "calculus  of  operations."      In 
this  branch  of  mathematics,  which 
is   peculiar  to  England,  the   sym- 
bols indicating  an  arithmetical  op- 


eration are  separated  from  those 
denoting  quantity  and  treated  as 
distinct  objects  of  calculation.  In 
connection  with  these  investiga- 
tions, many  of  which  have  now 
penetrated  into  ordinary  text- 
books, Boole  was  led  to  examine 
the  conditions  under  which  and  the 
forms  in  which  algebraical  expres- 
sions, whilst  undergoing  changes 
and  transformations,  remain,  never- 
theless, unaltered  (invariant)  (1841). 
By  introducing  this  point  of  view 
he  has,  so  to  speak,  created  modern 
algebra ;  founding  the  extensive 
and  fruitful  science  of  "  Invari- 
ants." Of  this  we  shall  treat 
later  on.  I  now  only  refer  to  the 
further  development  of  this  sub- 
ject in  the  hands  of  Cayley  and 
Sylvester,  and  to  the  valuable 
sketch  of  the  history  of  this  branch 
of  mathematics  by  Dr  F.  Mayer  in 
the  first  volume  of  the  '  Jahres- 
bericht  der  deutschen  Mathemati- 
ker-Vereinigung,'  Berlin,  1892. 


248 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


22. 
Babbage. 


wealthiest  of  nations  has  shown  to  scientific  genius  is 
to  be  found  in  the  history  of  Babbage's  calculating 
engine.  Yet  this  machine  was  approved  by  all  experts 
— English  and  foreign — during  the  inventor's  lifetime ; 
and  the  Eeport  of  a  Commission  of  the  British  Asso- 
ciation appointed  specially  to  examine  into  the  matter, 
concluded  by  stating  that  the  scheme  was  perfectly  feas- 
ible, and  might,  if  carried  out,  mark  an  invention  as  great 
probably  as  that  of  logarithms.1  Who  among  us  who 
has  been  interested  in  the  promotion  of  institutions  for 
higher  education  has  not  a  story  to  tell  of  pecuniary 
troubles,  continued  through  many  a  long  year,  whilst 
the  wealth  of  the  country  seemed  to  exert  its  influence 
only  in  the  direction  of  making  the  demands  on  a  strug- 
gling establishment  more  formidable,  the  expenses  more 
difficult  to  defray  ? 2 


1  On  Babbage  see  p.  233,  note  1. 
The  history  of  the  "  difference  en- 
gines "  and  the  "  analytical  engine  " 
is  given  by  Babbage  himself  in  his 
'Passages  from  the  Life  of  a  Phil- 
osopher.'    See  also  Weld,  '  History 
of  the  Royal  Society,'   vol.   ii.    p. 
369,  &c. 

2  Like  the  Royal  Society,  which 
for    a    century    had    to    struggle 
with   poverty,   the   Royal   Institu- 
tion  has  a  story   to   tell  of  want 
of  funds  through  a  long  period  of 
its    early    existence.       See    Bence 
Jones,     '  The    Royal    Institution,' 
London,  1871,  pp.  202,  281.     The 
Royal  Institution  was  founded  by 
Benjamin   Thomson,   Count   Rum- 
ford  (1753-1814),  and  had  origin- 
ally not  a  scientific,  hardly  even  a 
higher    educational    object.       The 
scheme   arose   in   the  mind  of  its 
founder  after  he  had  successfully 
exerted  himself  at  Munich   under 
the   patronage   of   the  Elector  of 


Bavaria  in  founding  industrial  work- 
houses, improving  the  state  of  the 
army,  and  putting  down  beggary 
and  immorality  in  the  capital  and 
country.  His  principle  was  to 
make  "  vicious  and  abandoned 
people  first  happy  and  then  virtu- 
ous" (p.  31).  After  leaving  Mun- 
ich in  1793  and  spending  two  years 
in  Italy,  similarly  occupied,  he 
visited  London  in  1795  in  order  to 
publish  his  Essays,  which  appeared 
separately  between  1796  and  1802. 
The  first  essay  contained  "a  pro- 
posal for  forming  in  London  by 
private  subscription  an  establish- 
ment for  feeding  the  poor  and  giv- 
ing them  useful  employment,  .  .  . 
connected  with  an  institution  for 
introducing  and  bringing  forward 
into  general  use  new  inventions 
and  improvements,"  &c.,  &c.  (p. 
44).  The  first  outcome  of  this  was 
the  formation  of  a  society  for  en- 
couraging industry  and  promoting 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


249 


But  it  is  hardly  the  duty  of  the  historian  of  thought  to 
record  that  which  belongs  more  to  the  impediments  of 
mental  progress  than  to  its  promotion,  were  it  not  that 
in  and  through  these  peculiar  circumstances  the  genius 
of  the  nation  has  developed  its  main  features,  its  strong 
character.  These  are  manifest  as  much  in  the  depart- 
ment of  science  as  they  are  in  general  literature  and  in 
the  institutions  of  practical  life.  British  science  through 
all  the  centuries,  since  the  time  of  Eoger  Bacon,  and 
in  spite  of  the  efforts  of  his  illustrious  namesake,  has 


23. 

Character- 
istics of 
English 
thought. 


the  welfare  of  the  poor.  William 
Wilberforce  was  one  of  the  original 
promoters  ;  Thomas  Bernard,  the 
founder  of  many  other  charitable 
institutions,  one  of  its  most  active 
members.  To  a  committee  of  this 
Society  Count  Rumford  submitted, 
in  1799,  his  proposals  for  forming 
the  Royal  Institution,  and  it  was 
accordingly  founded  in  February  of 
that  year  on  private  subscriptions 
of  fifty  guineas  each.  It  was  de- 
scribed as  a  "public  Institution 
for  diffusing  the  knowledge  and 
facilitating  the  general  introduc- 
tion of  useful  mechanical  inven- 
tions and  improvements,  and  for 
teaching  by  courses  of  philosophical 
lectures  and  experiments  the  appli- 
cation of  science  to  the  common 
purposes  of  life. "  In  the  course  of 
a  very  few  years  the  original  char- 
acter of  the  Institution  entirely 
changed,  the  aim  of  influencing 
directly  the  condition  of  the  poor 
was  lost  sight  of,  and  little  re- 
mained besides  the  result  of  "  bring- 
ing science  into  some  degree  of 
fashion  "  and  "  affording  a  new  em- 
ployment and  amusement  to  the 
higher  classes  of  life."  The  inter- 
est of  the  Institution  for  the  his- 
tory of  thought  is  the  fact  that  in 
its  laboratory  Davy  and  Faraday 


conducted  their  researches,  and  that 
they,  as  well  as  Young,  Coleridge, 
and  Sydney  Smith,  there  delivered 
their  lectures.  And  the  history  of 
the  Royal  Institution  is  also  typical 
of  the  history  of  other  establish- 
ments for  higher  culture  in  this 
country :  it  has  been  in  its  main 
features  repeated  on  a  larger  or 
smaller  scale  in  many  provincial 
societies,  and  notably  in  the  col- 
leges of  Manchester,  Birmingham, 
Liverpool,  Newcastle,  Leeds,  Bris- 
tol, Nottingham,  &c.  Started  by 
persons  with  large  but  nevertheless 
insufficient  means,  or  by  subscrip- 
tions and  endowments  of  moderate 
extent,  obliged  to  gain  popularity 
and  fashionable  support  in  order  to 
meet  their  growing  expenses,  these 
institutions  have  depended  mostly 
on  individual  energy  for  their  first 
successes,  and  have  all  had  to  pass 
through  periods  of  great  difficulty, 
till  in  course  of  years  they  have 
acquired  a  special  character  of  use- 
fulness and  defined  their  peculiar 
sphere  of  action.  The  absence  of 
a  definite  programme  and  a  great 
waste  of  energy  and  funds  over 
special  departures  are  not  un- 
common features  of  these  develop- 
ments. 


250 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


refused  to  congregate  in  distinct  schools  and  institutions 
or  to  be  localised  in  definite  centres.  The  Royal  Society, 
the  Royal  Institution,  the  British  Association,  and  many 
other  smaller  societies,  have  all  more  or  less  started  with 
the  programme  of  Lord  Bacon,  and  have  failed  to  realise 
it :  everywhere  the  schemes  of  co-operation  or  organised 
scientific  research  have  encountered  the  opposition  of 
individual  pursuits  or  of  local  interests. 

Newton  could  not  secure  the  use  of  Flamsteed's  obser- 
vations, which  on  their  part  remained  uncompleted  and 
unpublished  through  the  want  of  appreciation  of  others. 
Great  schemes  in  practical  life  have  been  carried  out 
by  the  unaided  efforts  of  eminent  persons,  and  great 
ideas  have  been  put  forward  with  all  the  power  and 
24.  all  the  resources  of  individual  genius,1  but  no  great 

Absence  of 

schools  of  master  in  scientific  research  in  this  country  can  point 
to  a  compact  following  of  pupils — to  a  school  which 
undertakes  to  finish  what  the  master  has  begun,  to  carry 
his  ideas  into  far  regions  and  outlying  fields  of  research, 
or  to  draw  their  remoter  consequences.  Xewtonianism 
was  a  creation  of  Voltaire;  the  school  of  Locke  is  to  be 
found  in  France ;  the  best  realisation  of  Bacon's  schemes 
are  the  Encyclopedic,  the  French  Institute,  and  the 
foreign  Academies.2  Dr  Young's  discoveries  in  optics 


scientific 
thought. 


1  See  Huxley,  '  Lav  Sermons, 
&c.,'  edition  of  1891,  p.* 43  :  "  Eng- 
land can  show  now,  as  she  has  been 
able  to  show  in  every  generation 
since  civilisation  spread  over  the 
West,  individual  men  who  hold 
their  own  against  the  world,  and 
keep  alive  the  old  tradition  of  her 
intellectual  eminence.  But  in  the 
majority  of  cases  these  men  are 
what  they  are  in  virtue  of  their 


native  intellectual  force,  and  of  a 
strength  of  character  which  will 
not  recognise  impediments.  They 
are  not  trained  in  the  courts  of 
the  Temple  of  Science,  but  storm 
the  walls  of  that  edifice  in  all  sorts 
of  irregular  ways,  and  with  much 
loss  of  time  and  power,  in  order  to- 
obtain  their  legitimate  positions." 
2  Sefe  above,  pp.  34,  95. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND.          251 

and  hieroglyphics  were  made  known  to  the  learned  world 
through  his  French  contemporaries.  Dalton,1  Charles 
Bell,2  Faraday,  Darwin,  and  Maxwell,  no  less  than 
Bentley  and  Gibbon,3  have  furnished  the  text  for  lecture- 
courses  in  German  universities,  and  created  a  whole 
literature  of  pamphlets  and  scientific  memoirs.4  English 
societies  may  sometimes  honour  and  admire,  but  they  do 
not  support,  their  great  representatives,  and  these  them- 
selves often  refuse  to  be  tied  by  exclusive  academic 
duties,  still  more  by  official  restrictions.  Two  charac- 
teristics have  marked  most  of  them :  they  have,  at  all 
expense  and  sacrifice,  guarded  their  individual  freedom  25. 
of  thought,  and  they  have  almost  always  shown  a  great  character 

and  practi- 

desire  to  combine  some  application  with  their  abstract  cai  tendency 

of  English 

researches,  to  take  part  in  the  great  practical  work  of  science- 
the  nation.  Continental  thinkers,  whose  lives  are  devoted 
to  the  realisation  of  some  great  ideal,  complain  of  the 
want  of  method,  of  the  erratic  absence  of  discipline,  which 
is  peculiar  to  English  genius.  The  fascination  which 
practical  interests  exert  in  this  country  appears  to  them 
an  absence  of  full  devotedness  to  purely  ideal  pursuits.5 

1  See  above,  p.  245,  note. 

2  See  above,  p.  193,  note. 

3  See  above,  p.  169,  note. 

4  Germany  may  be  said  to  have 
produced  Dcmvinismus  in  this  cen- 
tury as  France  created  Newtonian- 
isme  in  the   last.      Huxley  writes 
('Life  of  Darwin,'  vol.  ii.  p.  186) : 
"  None   of   us   dreamed   (in    1860) 
that  in  the  course  of  a  few  years 
the  strength  (and  perhaps  I  may 
add  the  weakness)  of  Darwinismus 
would  have  its  most  extensive  and 
most  brilliant  illustrations  in  the 
land  of  learning."     Quite  recently 
Prof.    Boltzmann   at  Munich,   and 
M.  Poiiicare',  have  published  courses 


of    lectures   on   Maxwell's    electric 
theories. 

5  What  appears  irksome  to  an 
English  genius — the  red  tape  of 
academic  restrictions,  the  barriers 
of  officialism,  and  the  duties  of  the 
teacher — melted  away  in  the  glow 
of  enthusiasm  and  love  of  truth 
which  animated  the  great  leaders 
and  founders  of  university  culture 
abroad  ;  as  Goethe  has  told  us  that 
the  rigid  form  of  the  sonnet  melts 
in  the  fervour  of  the  love-song  : 

"  Das  Allerstarrste  freudig  aufzuschmel- 

zen 

Muss  Liebesfeuer  allgewaltig  gltthen." 
— Sonette  No.  14. 


252  SCIENTIFIC  THOUGHT. 

The  English  man  of  science  would  reply  that  it  is  unsafe 
to  trust  exclusively  to  the  guidance  of  a  pure  idea,  that 
the  ideality  of  German  research  has  frequently  been 
identical  with  unreality,  and  that  in  no  country  has  so 
much  time  and  power  been  frittered  away  in  following 
phantoms,  and  in  systematising  empty  notions,  as  in  the 
Land  of  the  Idea ;  but  he  would  as  readily  admit  that 
his  own  country  is  greatly  deficient  in  such  organisations 
for  combined  scientific  labour  as  exist  abroad,  and  that 
England  possesses  no  well-trained  army  of  intellectual 
workers. 
26.  These  differences  between  English  and  Continental 

English  pe- 
culiarities    science  were  most  pronounced  in  the  first  half  of  the 

more  pro- 

Present;  century,  when  Germany  developed  her  university 
system,  when  France  clearly  defined  the  exact  scientific 
methods,  and  when  the  encyclopaedic  view — peculiar  to 
the  historical  and  philosophical  pursuits  of  the  earlier 
years — gradually  became  dominant  in  the  exact  sciences 
also.  Since  then  the  intercourse  of  the  different  nations 
has  done  much  to  destroy  these  national  peculiarities. 
The  reform  of  the  universities,  in  which  Germany  was 
engaged  in  the  early  years  of  the  century,  did  not  touch 
the  English  universities  before  the  middle  of  the  century. 
In  the  meantime  quite  different  demands  had  sprung  up 
all  through  the  civilised  world ;  and  as  nothing  repeats 
itself  in  history,  it  will  be  impossible  to  reach  in  this 
country  the  same  broad  organisation  for  purely  intellec- 
tual work  as  Germany  can  rightly  boast  of  during  the 
period  we  are  dealing  with.  Some  persons  doubt  whether 
it  will  be  maintained  in  Germany.  It  appears  still  more 
doubtful  whether  such  an  organisation  could  now  be 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


253 


created  in  the  face  of  the  industrial  spirit  of  our  age.  Ever 
since  the  latter  half  of  the  eighteenth  century  schemes  for 
a  general  education  of  the  masses  have  attracted  the 
thought  and  the  attention  of  philanthropists  and  states- 
men in  many  countries  of  Europe.  But  the  directions 
taken  by  these  educational  efforts  have  been  character- 
istically different  in  the  different  countries,  and  their  suc- 
cess, so  far  as  the  great  masses  of  the  people  are  con- 
cerned, has  been  very  partial  indeed.  It  is  true  that 
during  the  first  thirty  years  no  country  possessed  such 
distinguished  schools  of  science  as  did  France  in  the  great 
scientific  and  medical  institutions  of  her  capital.  It  is 
also  true  that  no  country  equalled  Germany  in  her  system 
of  universities  and  higher  schools,  which  had  come  under 
the  influence  of  classical  learning  and  philosophical  ideals. 
England,  which  at  that  time  took  no  part  in  the  educa- 
tional movements  of  the  Continent,1  possessed,  neverthe- 


1  This  statement  requires  two 
qualifications.  Firstly,  both  Milton 
and  Locke  have  had  great  influ- 
ence in  spreading  enlightened  views 
regarding  the  principles  and  the 
object  of  education  in  general — 
especially  in  the  direction  of  en- 
larging the  idea  of  education,  so  as 
to  make  it  comprise  something  more 
than  merely  instruction  and  pedan- 
tic teaching.  I  cannot  find,  how- 
ever, that  in  England,  either  in  the 
direction  of  higher  university  edu- 
cation or  of  a  general  system  of 
popular  education,  their  influence 
has  been  very  marked.  Locke's 
influence  abroad,  through  his  psy- 
chological analysis  of  the  mind,  has 
been  very  considerable.  Secondly, 
in  the  direction  of  practical  educa- 
tion, of  the  endeavour  to  reach 
large  numbers  of  the  people  by 
educational  institutions,  we  must 


look  with  admiration  to  the  early 
work  done  in  Scotland,  which  in 
this  respect  somewhat  resembles 
Switzerland.  The  Scotch  system  of 
parochial  schools,  and  their  influence 
on  the  education  of  the  people, 
has  been  too  little  studied  abroad, 
though  rightly  extolled  at  home.  It 
is  true  that,  with  the  exception  of 
Calvin,  none  of  the  great  Continen- 
tal educationalists — such  as  Fe"ne- 
Ion,  Rousseau,  Pestalozzi,  or  W. 
von  Humboldt — have  had  any  di- 
rect influence  on  Scotland  ;  nor  has 
the  educational  work  of  Scotland 
produced  any  great  educational 
literature  like  that  which  Switzer- 
land can  boast  [of,  and  which  has 
brought  the  theory  of  education 
so  prominently  before  the  world. 
But  nevertheless  there  it  stands, 
this  creation  of  John  Knox  and 
the  early  Reformers.  "Civilised 


254 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


27.        less,  something  peculiar   in  her   two  great  universities, 
character  of  It  was  neither  the  scientific,  nor  the  classical,  nor  the 

Knglish  uni- 
versities,     philosophical  spirit  exclusively  which  reigned  there ;  if 

any  or  all  of  them  had  ruled,  we  should  not  meet  with 
those  repeated  complaints  that  higher  mathematics  were 
absent  in  Cambridge,  that  no  philological  studies  were 
cultivated  in  either  of  the  universities,  and  that  philosophy 
was  represented  merely  by  Aristotle,  Butler,  Locke,  and 
Paley.1  According  to  the  representatives  of  the  university 


Europe  has  never  witnessed  a  nobler 
spectacle  than  the  first  Protestants 
of  Scotland  in  the  assembly  of  the 
nation  demanding  that  from  the 
funds  before  abused  by  a  licentious 
superstition  one  -  third  should  be 
devoted,  not  to  increase  the  rev- 
enue of  the  Reformed  Church,  but 
to  the  education,  the  universal  edu- 
cation, of  the  youth  in  all  depart- 
ments of  instruction,  from  the  high- 
est to  the  lowest"  ('North  Brit. 
Rev.,'  12,  p.  483). 

1  As  to  the  deficient  mathemati- 
cal teaching  at  Cambridge,  see  p. 
233,  note,  &c.  The  complaints  re- 
garding the  teaching  of  other  sub- 
jects are  frequent,  but  belong  to  a 
later  date,  the  middle  of  the  century, 
when  the  Royal  Commission  of  In- 
quiry, which  was  appointed  under 
the  Government  of  Lord  John  Rus- 
sell on  the  31st  August  1850  and 
expired  with  the  presentation  of  its 
report  on  the  30th  August  1852, 
attracted  the  attention  of  the  pub- 
lic to  university  reform,  aud  gave 
rise  to  a  very  full  discussion  of  the 
whole  subject  in  the  various  liter- 
ary papers  and  reviews.  The  two 
older  universities  are  called  "cita- 
dels of  political  prejudice  and  sec- 
tarian exclusiveness,  instead  of  be- 
ing the  temples  of  liberal  arts  and 
the  repositories  of  science"  ('Brit. 
Quart.  Review,'  1860,  July,  p.  205). 
Theology  is  stated  to  be  "  the  last 


thing  taught  at  Cambridge  "  (ibid. , 
p.  221);  there  was  no  professor  of 
Latin,  none  of  English  literature, 
of  logic  and  metaphysics,  of  modern 
languages  (p.  225).  In  1849  Cam- 
bridge had  no  laboratory  ;  the  uni- 
versities took  no  part  in  the  legal 
training  of  lawyers  ('Edin.  Rev.,' 
April  1849,  p.  511) ;  Oxford  afforded 
no  training  in  natural  science  (ibid.) 
Cambridge  "  sacrificed  to  the  mon- 
opoly of  a  severe  geometry  every 
other  exercise  and  attainment  of 
the  human  mind.  There  was  no 
theological  study,  no  study  of  his- 
tory, none  of  moral  science,  none  of 
chemistry,  none  even  of  experi- 
mental philosophy"  (ibid.,  p.  514). 
These  criticisms  were  fully  justified 
by  the  Reports  of  the  Commissions 
published  in  1852.  See  on  the  teach- 
ing of  Theology  at  Cambridge,  Re- 
port, pp.  89, 102  ;  Evidence,  pp.  88, 
168,  190,  216  :  on  the  teaching  of 
Latin,  Rep. ,  pp.  98,  102  ;  Evid.,  pp. 
165,  176,  289  :  on  the  teaching  of 
English,  Evidv  pp.  124, 136 :  of  mo- 
dern Languages,  Rep.,  pp.  26,  101  ; 
Evid.,  pp.  165,  216,  300 :  of  Law, 
Rep.,  pp.  35,  182  ;  Evid.,  pp.  123, 
190  :  of  Natural  Sciences,  Evid.,  p. 
115,  &c.  In  1874  the  'Edinburgh 
Review '  could  point  out  that  during 
twenty  years,  whilst  the  examination 
for  the  Indian  Civil  Service  had  been 
thrown  open,  the  English  universi- 
ties had  practically  contributed  no 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


255 


system,  what  England  did  possess  was  the  ideal  of  a  liberal       as. 
education.     But  none  of  these  three  forms  of  intellectual  Liberal 

cation. 

training — neither  the  scientific  in  Paris,  nor  the  classical 
in  Germany,  still  less  the  liberal  in  England — touched 
the  great  masses  of  the  people.  They  all  did  good  work 
in  their  respective  lines ;  but  they  left,  or  would  by  them- 
selves have  left,  the  country  in  darkness.  The  begin- 
nings of  general  popular  education  are  to  be  traced 
independently  in  Switzerland,  in  Scotland,  and  in  many 
of  the  small  States  of  Germany.1  The  great  scientific 


candidates  to  the  competition  (April 
1874,  p.  342).  "  Nothing  about  uni- 
versity life  was  more  striking "  to 
the  Edinburgh  Reviewer  "than  the 
contrast  between  the  efforts  and 
the  high  aims  of  the  few,  the 
culture  and  solid  result  achieved 
by  them — and  the  utter  uselessness 
of  it  to  the  many  "  (p.  354).  The 
'Quarterly  Review'  of  June  1826 
notes  "  a  growing  taste  for  the 
cultivation  of  physical  science  as 
characteristic  of  the  state  of  the 
public  mind  in  England"  (p.  159), 
and  refers  to  the  "  measures  which 
have  been  carried  into  effect 
throughout  the  country  with  great 
harmony  of  design,  although  chiefly 
by  the  unassisted  exertions  of  pri- 
vate individuals,  .  .  .  the  recent 
establishment  of  numerous  literary 
and  philosophical  institutions  in  our 
metropolis  and  many  of  our  pro- 
vinces "  (ibid.,  p.  154). 

1  The  great  Reformers — Luther, 
Melanchthon,  Zwingli,  and  Calvin — 
alike  took  a  great  interest  in  educa- 
tion, which  they  intended  to  be  uni- 
versal and  popular.  But  their  suc- 
cess, so  far  as  the  education  of  the 
people  was  concerned,  remained 
everywhere  very  partial.  A  real  or- 
ganisation of  primary  schools  was 
not  attained.  They  prepared  for 
it  by  introducing  the  vernacular 


languages,  the  reading  of  the  Bible, 
the  popular  hymns.  Their  main 
efforts  lay  in  the  training  of  good 
teachers  for  church  and  schools  in 
the  reorganisation  of  what  were 
called  the  Latin  schools.  In  the 
course  of  the  sixteenth  and  seven- 
teenth centuries  the  smaller  Protes- 
tant States  of  Germany — especially 
Saxony,  Wiirtemberg,  Brunswick, 
the  northern  cities  Hamburg  and 
Liibeck — received  under  various 
forms  what  was  called  "  Eine  Kir- 
chen-  und  Schulordnung."  Luther's 
tract  of  the  year  1524,  addressed 
to  the  "burgomasters  and  coun- 
cillors of  all  towns  of  the  German 
land,  that  they  should  found  and 
maintain  Christian  schools,"  was 
the  beginning  of  this  movement. 
In  Scotland  burgh  schools,  also 
grammar  (or  Latin)  schools  and 
lecture  schools,  "in  which  the 
children  were  instructed  to  read 
the  vernacular  language,"  existed 
long  before  the  Reformation.  But 
to  John  Knox  is  due  the  scheme 
for  popular  education  contained  in 
the  '  First  Book  of  Discipline.'  The 
parochial  schools  were  started  in 
many  instances  by  voluntary  or  ec- 
clesiastical assessment  through  the 
efforts  of  the  Reformed  clergy. 
The  foundation  of  the  subsequent 
system  of  parochial  schools  was  laid 


256 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


schools  of  France  trained  the  civil  and  military  engin- 
eers in  that  country,  and  produced  text-books  for  the 


in  the  statute  of  1696.  It  must 
not  be  forgotten,  however,  that  the 
"  Order  of  Jesus  "  (founded  1540), 
whose  higher  educational  work  has 
found  so  much  appreciation  from 
men  like  Sturm — the  Protestant 
educationalist  —  Lord  Bacon,  and 
Descartes  (see  the  quotations  in 
Schmidt's  '  Geschichte  der  Piidago- 
gik,'  4th  ed.,  vol.  ii.  p.  248),  was  also 
active  in  the  direction  of  popular 
and  primary  education.  In  emula- 
tion of  the  Protestant  movement, 
it  had  introduced  "school  regula- 
tions "  in  many  Catholic  countries, 
and  even  founded  a  special  order 
— the  "Patres  piarum  scholarum  " 
(1600) — for  the  education  of  the 
poorer  classes  (ibid.,  p.  253).  Whe- 
ther the  statute  of  1696  is  the  ear- 
liest official  document  referring  to 
popular  education  and  providing  the 
means  of  maintaining  an  adequate 
number  of  schools  (one  in  1000  of 
population)  to  teach  the  lower 
classes,  I  cannot  say.  It  appears 
that  Duke  Ernest  of  Gotha,  in  the 
course  of  the  seventeenth  century, 
established  a  general  system  of 
primary  education  in  his  terri- 
tory which  was  "quite  unique,  at 
first  an  object  of  ridicule,  but  then 
very  soon  of  emulation"  (ibid.,  p. 
333).  The  regulations  were  cer- 
tainly most  wise  and  liberal,  and 
attendance  was  made  compulsory. 
The  question  of  popular  education 
was  taken  up  on  a  much  larger 
scale  by  Frederick  the  Great  in  the 
middle  of  the  eighteenth  century. 
The  year  1763,  which  marks  the 
end  of  the  Seven  Years'  War,  is 
also  the  year  of  an  edict  which 
forms  the  basis  of  the  regulation 
of  popular  education  for  the  whole 
monarchy :  it  establishes  village 
schools  with  compulsory  attend- 
ance. It  met  with  much  opposi- 
tion, and  its  ends  were  only  slowly 


realised,  and  only  as  training-schools, 
where  a  sufficient  number  of  teach- 
ers were  educated,  sprang  up,  and 
as  popular  school  and  story-books 
were  provided.  Campe,  with  his 
edition  of  '  Robinson  Crusoe,'  marks 
an  epoch  in  this  direction.  In  fact, 
the  cause  of  universal  popular  edu- 
cation remained  in  the  hands  of 
private  persons,  frequently  of  men 
of  great  insight  and  organising 
ability — such  as  A.  H.  Fran  eke 
(1663-1727),  the  indefatigable  friend 
of  the  poor  and  of  orphans  ;  Base- 
dow  (1723-90),  the  founder  of  the 
Philanthropin  and  populariser  of 
Rousseau's  ideas ;  Von  Rochow 
(1734-1805),  the  friend  of  the  coun- 
try -  folk  and  founder  of  village 
schools ;  Von  Felbiger  (1724-88), 
the  adviser  of  Maria  Theresa  and 
Joseph  II.,  the  organiser  of  the 
popular  educational  system  in  Aus- 
tria (1770-80) :  or  else  it  was  de- 
pendent on  the  casual  favour  of 
enlightened  princes  and  sovereigns. 
At  length,  in  the  middle  of  the 
eighteenth  century,  training-schools 
for  teachers,  so-called  "seminaries," 
were  founded  all  over  Germany.  A 
beginning  had  been  made  by  Duke 
Ernest  of  Gotha  (1601-75),  but 
had  been  neglected  like  many 
other  beginnings.  But  in  the 
second  half  of  the  eighteenth  cen- 
tury no  less  than  thirty-three  semi- 
naries were  founded  all  over  Ger- 
many, including  Austria.  For  details 
on  this  important  and  interesting 
subject,  see  the  third  volume  of 
Schmidt's  '  Geschichte  der  Pada- 
gogik. '  Freytag's  '  Bilder  aus  der 
deutschen  Vergangenheit'  also  con- 
tains many  interesting  details  ;  but 
above  all  I  would  recommend  for 
the  countries  of  the  west  and  south 
of  Germany  the  valuable  researches 
of  C.  T.  Perthes  contained  in  his 
'  Politische  Zustande  und  Personen 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


257 


higher  scientific  training  of  the  whole  of  Europe ; l  but 
no  serious  effort  was  made,  during  the  brilliant  days  of 
the  First  Empire,  to  secure  for  the  nation  the  blessing  of 
a  popular  education.  This  state  of  things  continued 
under  the  Eestoration ;  the  real  beginnings  of  an  or- 
ganised primary  system  are  to  be  found  in  Guizot's 
celebrated  law  of  1833.  In  Germany  the  influence  of 
Pestalozzi  and  Zschokke  in  the  south;  of  Basedow,Francke, 
and  the  school  of  Kant  and  Herder,  and,  later,  of  Herbart 
in  the  north, — stimulated  many  Governments  to  establish 
a  system  of  popular  schools  for  the  education  of  the  masses, 
and  a  system  of  seminaries  for  the  training  of  a  popu- 
lar teaching  staff.  This  movement  was  chiefly  carried 
on  independently  of  the  reform  of  the  universities  and 
higher  schools,  over  which  the  ideal  of  Wissenschaft  ex- 
ercised a  powerful  spell.  Under  the  latter  were  trained 
the  leaders  and  higher  teachers  of  the  nation,  as  well  as 
the  members  of  the  learned  professions.  The  educational 
influence  of  this  ideal  on  the  more  gifted  among  the 
student  class  was  the  very  highest  and  best ;  but  it  hardly 


in  Deutschland  zur  Zeit  der  fran- 
zosischen  Herrschaft,'  2  vols.,  Gotha, 
1862  and  1869.  As  unfortunately 
this  work,  with  its  collection  of 
interesting  and  not  easily  accessible 
facts  referring  to  the  inner  history 
of  the  German  people,  has  no  index, 
I  give  the  following  references : 
Compulsory  education  in  Kur  Trier 
in  1712,  vol.  i.  p.  225  ;  in  Kurmainz, 
1750,  vol.  i.  p.  19  ;  popular  educa- 
tion in  Baden,  vol.  i.  p.  411 ;  in 
Bavaria,  vol.  i.  pp.  436,  467  ;  in 
Wiirtemberg,  vol.  i.  p.  537  ;  and  the 
chapter  on  Joseph  II. 's  school  re- 
form, vol.  i.  pp.  153-170.  The  sem- 
inary or  training-school  being  thus 
VOL.  I. 


the  centre  and  beginning  of  na- 
tional education  in  Germany,  as  it 
has  also,  with  a  different  constitu- 
tion, become  the  centre  of  scientific 
work  (see  p.  214,  note),  it  is  inter- 
esting to  note  that  Scotland,  so  far 
advanced  in  educational  work,  had 
no  real  training-school  for  teachers 
before  Stow  started  his  Normal 
School  in  Glasgow  (see  '  Cham- 
bers's  Encyclopaedia,'  art.  "  Educa- 
tion "),  and  that  the  "  seminary  " 
for  higher  scientific  work  has  to 
this  day  not  yet  been  introduced 
into  this  country. 

1  See  above,  p.  44,  note. 


B 


258 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


29. 

Union  of 


reached  the  multitude  of  less  gifted  minds,  who  always 
gave  themselves  to  bread-studies  ;  and  it  must  necessarily 
fail  yet  more  when  not  only  the  future  teachers  and 
leaders,  but  the  masses  of  the  nation,  flock  into  the  halls  of 
the  universities.  Imperceptibly  a  differentiation  has  taken 
place  in  Germany  between  the  educational  work  which 
was  meant  to  reach  the  people  at  large  and  the  intellectual 
instruction  of  a  select  few.  But  it  is  exactly  this  differ- 
en^ati°n  °^  education  and  higher  instruction  which  the 
champions  of  a  liberal  education  in  England  have  desired 
to  avoid.1  In  France,  very  soon  after  Eousseau's  time,  dis- 


1  The  two  developments  in  Ger- 
many start  from  different  centres. 
The  purely  educational  movement 
began  in  Switzerland  with  Pestal- 
ozzi  (1746-1827).  His  forerunner 
was  Martin  Planta  (1727-1772),  his 
successors  were  legion,  all  over 
Europe,  including  sovereigns,  states- 
men, and  philosophers.  He  created 
an  enthusiasm  for  education,  which 
was  to  begin  at  home,  not  in  the 
school ;  to  depend  on  the  influence  of 
the  mother  ;  to  be  founded  on  a  re- 
ligious spirit ;  to  direct  itself  to  the 
development  of  the  body  as  much  as 
of  the  mind ;  to  rest  primarily  on  ob- 
servation and  experience,  not  mainly 
on  memory  and  learning  ;  and  then 
to  absorb  the  whole  mind  and  the 
entire  man,  not  exclusively  the  in- 
tellect. It  was  to  begin  from  be- 
low, not  from  above,  with  the 
people,  the  poor,  the  unfortunate 
and  deserted  ;  on  the  part  of  the 
teacher  it  was  to  be  a  sacrifice, 
an  end  in  itself,  not  a  profession. 
The  greatest  followers  of  Pestalozzi 
were  Von  Fellenberg  (1771-1844), 
the  founder  of  Hofwyl  and  other 
industrial  schools  for  poor  and  de- 
serted children  among  the  peasant 
population  of  Switzerland ;  Johan- 
nes Falk  (1760-1826),  the  founder 


of  a  great  number  of  houses  for  the 
poor  and  the  fallen,  of  the  "So- 
ciety of  Friends  in  Need  "  ;  J.  H. 
Wichern  (1808-1881),  the  founder 
of  the  "  Rauhe  Haus "  near  Ham- 
burg ;  lastly,  the  celebrated  Frobel 
(1782-1852,  a  native  of  Thiiringen), 
the  founder  of  the  Kindergarten. 
The  other — not  to  say  opposite — 
development  was  centred  in  F.  A. 
Wolf,  in  whose  school  the  ideal  of 
Wissenschaft  with  its  enormous  in- 
fluence on  universities  and  high 
schools  was  elaborated.  In  the 
history  of  this  development,  with 
which  our  second  chapter  dealt, 
the  name  of  Pestalozzi  does  not 
occur.  The  term  "  popular  "  was 
for  a  time  banished  as  identical 
with  the  Bavavvia  of  the  ancient 
Greeks.  The  two  movements  find 
a  connecting-link  in  the  extra-aca- 
demical, the  classical  literature  of 
Germany,  notably  of  Herder  and 
Goethe,  to  whom  we  must  add 
Fichte  and  Schleiermacher.  The 
present  age  is  working  towards 
a  fusion  of  both  interests,  of  the 
educational  and  higher  scientific, 
the  bridging  over  of  the  gap  which 
had  been  left ;  it  is  trying  to  re- 
move the  estrangement  which  ex- 
isted in  the  middle  of  the  century.. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


259 


cussions  on  educational  matters  confine  themselves  to  the 
ends  and  means  of  general  or  higher  instruction ; l  in 


We  may  say  that  no  educational 
scheme  can  be  permanently  satis- 
factory that  does  not  regard  with 
equal  favour,  and  does  not  find  equal 
room  for,  the  two  ideals  of  Pestal- 
ozzi  and  Wolf.  It  is  interesting, 
however,  to  note  that  neither  in 
Switzerland  nor  in  Scotland,  the 
two  countries  in  which  popular 
education  has  been  longest  at 
home,  do  we  find  a  really  great 
development  of  the  higher  institu- 
tions and  centres  of  learning  ;  the 
universities  in  these  two  countries 
have  always  stood  somewhat  in  the 
relation  of  higher  schools  to  the 
rest  of  the  educational  establish- 
ments ;  but  both  countries  have 
produced  and  reared  some  of  the 
greatest  geniuses  of  all  time — geni- 
uses who  have  given  to  German 
and  English  literature  and  science  a 
fame  over  the  whole  world  and  for 
all  ages  ;  they  would  have  sufficed, 
had  they  stayed  at  home,  to  form 
academies  and  universities  of  the 
first  order. 

1  Compare  chapter  i.  pp.  112, 142, 
&c.  We  are  indebted  to  France 
for  three  great  educational  influ- 
ences which  have  left  indelible  traces 
.over  the  whole  domain  of  European 
thought.  These  proceed  from  the 
Paris  University,  the  model  of  higher 
education  ;  the  great  school  of  Port 
Royal,  that  model  of  secondary 
education  ;  and  the  '  Emile '  of 
Rousseau,  which  gave  to  the  edu- 
cational aspirations  of  Basedow,  of 
Kant,  and  of  Pestalozzi  a  definite 
direction.  It  has,  however,  fre- 
quently been  stated  that  the  val- 
uable side  of  Rousseau's  ideas 
was  developed  outside  of  France. 
"  C'est  une  chose  remarquable," 
says  M.  Compayre",  "  que  1'influence 
du  philosophe  de  Geneve  se  soit 
surtout  exerce"e  a  I'e'tranger,  en 
Allemagne  et  en  Suisse "  ('  His- 


toire  critique  des  Doctrines  de 
1'Education  en  France,'  5me  ed., 
1885,  vol.  ii.  p.  101).  "II  y  avait, 
chez  Rousseau,"  says  M.  Breal, 
"  un  cote  ge"nereux  et  vivifiant : 
1'amour  de  I'humanite"  et  particu- 
lierement  de  1'enfant,  la  confiance 
dans  ses  f  acuity's  et  le  respect  de  son 
activit^  intellectuelle.  Cette  partie 
la,  qui  e"tait  le  germe  de  vie  depose" 
dans  les  ceuvres  de  Rousseau,  nous 
1'avons  laissee  aux  Strangers."  In 
French  writers  a  great  deal  of  dis- 
cussion is  to  be  found  on  the  differ- 
ence between  education  and  in- 
struction. Duclos  (1704-72)  in  his 
celebrated  '  Considerations  sur  les 
mceurs  de  ce  siecle '  (1751),  in 
the  second  chapter,  which  treats  of 
Education  and  Prejudice,  says :  "  On 
trouve  parmi  nous  beaucoup  d'in- 
struction  et  peu  d'eVlucation.  On 
y  forme  des  savants,  des  artistes 
de  toute  espece  ;  chaque  partie  des 
lettres,  des  sciences  et  des  arts  y 
est  cultive"e  avec  succes,  par  des 
me"thodes  plus  ou  moins  conven- 
ables.  Mais  on  ne  s'est  pas  encore 
avise"  de  former  des  hommes,  c'est 
a  dire,  de  les  elever  respectivement 
les  uns  pour  les  autres,  de  faire- 
porter  sur  une  base  d'education 
gdneVale  toutes  les  instructions  par- 
ticulieres,"  &c.  When  the  successive- 
Governments  of  the  Revolution  took 
up  the  question  of  a  national  edu- 
cation, the  formula  of  Condorcet 
quite  inevitably  became  more  and 
more  the  leading  principle.  Con- 
dorcet distinguished  "  instruction  " 
— i.e.,  knowledge  positive  and  cer- 
tain, truths  of  fact  and  calculation 
— from  "education" — i.e.,  "politi- 
cal and  religious  beliefs."  He  gives ; 
the  State  the  power  to  extend  the 
former,  whilst  he  denies  it  the  right 
to  direct  and  dispense  the  latter  (see 
Hippeau,  '  L'Instruction  publique 
en  France  pendant  la  Revolution,' 


260 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


Germany,  education  and  higher  instruction  present  in- 
dependent developments ;  in  England  alone  the  genius 
and  language  of  the  nation  have  refused  to  admit  of  any 
curtailment  of  the  original  sense  of  the  word.  This  con- 
tinued to  imply  a  discipline  of  the  character  as  well  as 
of  the  mind,  practical  as  well  as  intellectual  training. 
So  much  has  been  said  in  this  country  and  abroad  re- 
garding the  shortcomings  of  the  English  universities  and 
higher  schools,  that  I  feel  it  a  duty  to  point  to  the  posi- 
tive gain  which  this  ideal  of  a  liberal  education1  has 


1881,  vol.  L  p.  xvii ;  also  Compayre, 
toe.  eit.t  voL  ii.  p.  280,  &c.)  Every 
Government  which  has  attempted 
to  systematise,  to  centralise  educa- 
tion, has  been  forced  also  to  secu- 
larise it,  to  reduce  it  to  instruction, 
leaving  out  what  many  consider  the 
central  problem  of  education,  the 
training  of  the  character  and  the 
discipline  of  the  feelings  and  the 
heart.  Considering  the  large  organ- 
isations which  have  been  developed 
in  England  by  the  unaided  efforts 
of  working  men,  such  as  the  trade- 
unions  and  theco-operative  societies, 
and  looking  at  the  amount  of  self- 
government,  self-control,  and  self- 
denial  which  they  demand  from 
then"  members,  one  might  be  tempt- 
ed to  say  that  England  is  the  best 
educated,  though  it  may  be  the 
worst  taught  and  the  least  informed, 
of  the  three  nations  now  under 
review. 

1  The  term  "liberal  education" 
has  acquired  a  peculiar  significance 
in  the  history  of  English  culture 
and  thought.  It  cannot  be  trans- 
lated into  French  or  German  with 
any  certainty  that  the  real  signifi- 
cance of  the  term  or  the  subject 
which  it  denotes  is  conveyed.  It  is 
interesting  to  note  how  each  of  the 
three  nations  has  given  to  special 
words  of  the  once  common  Latin 


language  a  peculiar  pregnancy,  de- 
noting a  peculiar  form  of  thought 
or  culture  which  they  have  especi- 
ally elaborated.  Thus  "science" 
in  the  modern  sense  is  a  product  of 
French  thought,  Wissenschaft  a  pro- 
duct of  German  thought.  England 
has  reserved  to  itself  the  elabora- 
tion of  a  "  liberal  education."  I  am 
at  a  loss  how  to  translate  it  into 
French,  unless  I  am  permitted  to 
use  simply  the  word  education  in 
its  contrast  to  instruction  and  en- 
seignement,  not  as  this  was  defined 
by  Condorcet,  but  as  it  is  under- 
stood in  the  writings  of  modern 
French  educationalists,  such  as 
Greard,  Breal,  Compayre,  and 
others.  To  convey  the  meaning 
of  "liberal  education"  to  a  Ger- 
man, I  would  revert  to  the  Greek 
phrase,  the  f\€v6epios  rcuSda  of  the 
post  -  classical  age.  The  fact  is 
that  down  to  the  middle  of  the 
century  the  Germans  in  discussions 
on  the  work  of  universities  and 
high  schools  always  talk  of  Wissen- 
schaft,  English  writers  always  talk  of 
"  liberal  education/'  To  a  German 
scholar's  heart  Wi-sse nschaft  is  dear 
beyond  anything ;  to  an  English 
university  man  it  is  "liberal  edu- 
cation." The  former  will  sacrifice 
everything  to  Wisstnschaft ;  the 
latter  will  not  part  with  "liberal 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


261 


been.  For  it  is  the  principal  object  of  this  work  to 
attempt  to  portray  the  actual  progress  of  thought,  the 
valuable  contributions  of  each  of  the  three  nations  to  the 


education."  In  Germany,  the  real 
home  of  the  educationalist  or  Er- 
zieher  has  not  been  the  university  ; 
the  home  of  the  man  of  science  has 
not  been  and  is  not  the  university 
in  England.  The  German  educa- 
tionalist can  point  to  a  special  crea- 
tion of  his  own,  the  Volksschule. 
The  English  man  of  science  has 
no  organisation  to  point  to  except 
it  be  the  select  society  of  a  dozen 
great  names  of  world -wide  fame, 
corresponding  to  the  solitary  and 
unconnected  heights  of  Homer,  So- 
phocles, Dante,  Shakespeare,  and 
Goethe  in  literature.  To  descend, 
however,  from  generalities  to  the 
real  thing,  I  give  here  some  ex- 
tracts referring  to  English  univer- 
sity life,  chosen  from  among  hun- 
dreds, all  variations  on  the  same 
theme.  Dr  Thomas  Young,  who 
knew  both  German  and  English 
universities,  having  studied  at  Got- 
tingen  and  taken  his  degree  at 
Cambridge,  was  not  indebted  to 
any  university  for  his  position  or 
his  knowledge  ;  yet  he  significantly 
defends  the  English  universities 
against  the  criticism  of  the  Edin- 
burgh Reviewer :  "  We  do  not  in- 
tend to  imply  a  censure  of  the 
system  adopted  by  our  universities  ; 
.  .  .  for  it  must  be  remembered 
that  the  advancement  of  learning  is 
by  no  means  the  principal  object  of 
an  academical  institution  :  the  diffu- 
sion of  a  respectable  share  of  in- 
struction in  literature  and  in  the 
sciences  among  those  classes  which 
hold  the  highest  situations  and  have 
the  most  extensive  influence  in  the 
State  is  an  object  of  more  import- 
ance to  the  public  than  the  dis- 
covery of  new  truths.  .  .  .  We 
think  that  we  have  observed  num- 
erous instances,  both  in  public  life 


and  in  the  pursuit  of  natural  know- 
ledge, in  which  great  scholars  and 
great  mathematicians  have  reasoned 
less  soundly,  although  more  ingeni- 
ously, than  others,  who,  being  some- 
what more  completely  in  the  pos- 
session of  common -sense,  .  .  .  were 
still  far  inferior  to  them  in  the  re- 
finements of  learning  or  of  science  " 
('  Quarterly  Review,'  May  1810, 
reprinted  in  Miscellaneous  Works, 
vol.  i.  p.  235,  &c.)  I  shall  now 
give  a  quotation  from  an  entirely 
different  source,  from  one  who  in 
his  department  was  equally  well 
acquainted  with  German  and  Eng- 
lish thought  and  life.  In  1830  E. 
B.  Pusey  attempted  to  give  his 
friend,  Prof.  Tholuck  of  Halle,  a 
sketch  of  what  had  been  "  recently 
done  in  English  theology."  He 
begins  by  referring  to  the  "prac- 
tical character  of  the  nation"  and 
"  the  different  condition  of  the  uni- 
versities," and  then  continues  as 
follows  :  "  Few,  if  any,  of  our  writ- 
ings have  originated  in  an  abstract 
love  of  investigation  :  our  greatest 
and  some  immortal  works  have 
arisen  in  some  exigencies  of  the 
times.  ...  A  German  writes  be- 
cause he  has  something  to  say  ;  an 
Englishman  only  because  it  is,  or 
he  thinks  it  is,  needed"  ('Life  of 
Pusey,'  vol.  i.  p.  238).  The  man 
who  did  most  for  the  widening  of 
the  circle  of  university  studies  in 
England  during  the  first  half  of  the 
century  was  William  Whewell  (1794- 
1866),  whose  influence  at  Cambridge 
extended  over  more  than  a  genera- 
tion. In  the  beginning  he  assisted 
the  movement  begun  by  Babbage, 
Herschel,  and  Peacock,  and  pub- 
lished several  text -books  on  me- 
chanics and  dynamics,  in  which  the 
influence  of  Continental,  especially 


262 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


so. 

Educational 

organisa- 

tions  in 

England. 


general  stock  of  ideal  possessions,  not  merely  to  criticise 
the  shortcomings  and  failures  of  separate  schools  of 
thought,  or  separate  sources  of  mental  development. 
Only  in  the  aggregate  of  these  different  ideals  is  to  be 
found  the  inventory  of  the  intellectual  possessions,  the 
outcome  of  the  higher  work  of  the  century. 

When  the  modern  scientific  methods  and  their  impel- 
ling  force,  the  mathematical  spirit,  made  their  way  from 
France  to  Germany  during  the  first  quarter  of  the  century, 


French  models,  can  be  clearly  traced. 
Between  1830  and  1850  his  influence 
exerted  itself  in  two  directions, 
firstly  by  the  publication  of  his 
'  History  of  the  Inductive  Sciences ' 
(3  vols.  1837  ;  a  second  edition  ap- 
peared in  1847,  a  third  in  1857),  and, 
secondly,  by  a  series  of  papers  and 
pamphlets  referring  to  university 
education.  As  the  ideal  and  defini- 
tion of  this  Whewell  adopts  the  term 
"liberal  education."  The  first  of 
these  papers  appeared  in  the '  British 
Critic'  (No.  17,  1831,  "Science  of 
the  English  Universities").  Then 
followed  in  1836  "  Thoughts  on  the 
study  of  Mathematics  "  ;  "  Addi- 
tional Thoughts,"  1836;  "On  the 
Principles  of  English  University 
Education,"  1837;  "Of  a  Liberal 
Education  in  General"  (Part  1, 
1845  ;  Part  2,  1850  ;  Part  3,  1852). 
The  second  part  of  the  little  work  on 
Liberal  Education  gives  a  history 
of  the  various  changes  previous  to 
1850  through  which  the  University 
of  Cambridge  tried  to  meet  the 
growing  demands  of  the  times  for 
a  wider  and  more  liberal  programme 
of  higher  scientific  work.  In  these 
various  writings  the  work  of  educa- 
tion and  "  original  research"  (a  term 
introduced  by  Whewell — see  Tod- 
hunter,  '  Life  of  Dr  Whewell,'  vol.  i. 
p.  50),  the  nature  of  "  permanent" 
and  "progressive"  studies  at  the 
university,  of  "  university "  and 


"  college  "  education,  of  "  tutorial  " 
and  "  professorial "  teaching,  are  fully 
discussed.  In  the  course  of  thirty 
years  the  university  of  Cambridge 
added  to  the  examinations  for  ma- 
thematical honours  the  "  Classical " 
Tripos  (1822),  the  "  Moral  Sciences  " 
Tripos  and  the  "  Natural  Sciences  " 
Tripos  (1848);  also  a  "Board  of 
Mathematical  Studies  "  (1848).  Dr 
Whewell's  great  influence  declined 
when  in  1850  Royal  Commissions 
were  appointed  to  "inquire  into 
the  state,  discipline,  studies,  and 
revenues  of  the  universities  of  Ox- 
ford and  Cambridge."  He  "regarded 
the  Commission  as  an  unwarranted 
and  undesirable  intrusion  into  the 
affairs  of  the  university."  The 
results  of  this  inquiry  belong  to 
the  second  half  of  the  century. 
Although  this  movement,  which 
was  brought  about  by  many  in- 
fluences, has  somewhat  changed  the 
issues,  the  central  idea  which  in 
England  tries  to  assimilate  the 
higher  work  and  thought  of  the 
nation  is  that  of  education.  The 
term  liberal  education,  which  for 
twenty  years,  from  1830  to  1850, 
formed  the  banner  of  university 
reform,  has  since  somewhat  yielded 
to  "scientific,"  and  more  recently 
to  "  technical,"  education  ;  the  in- 
fluence of  the  universities  has  gone 
out  in  the  work  of  university  exten- 
sion in  the  provincial  towns ;  still 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


263 


they  there  met  with  a  powerful  intellectual  organisation, 
the  German  university  system,  in  which  classical  and  philo- 
sophical studies  had  elaborated  the  ideal  of  Wissenschaft 
— of  science  in  the  larger  sense  of  the  word.  Gradually, 
and  not  without  opposition,  the  exact  or  mathematical 
spirit  was  received  into  this  system,  and  has  since  become 
an  integral  portion  of  it.  In  England  the  older  traditions 
which  clung  to  the  two  great  universities,  and  the  higher 


the  whole  movement  can  be  de- 
nned as  an  educational  movement. 
Whereas  in  Germany  about  a  gen- 
eration earlier  the  term  Wissenschaft 
gained  the  upper  hand  and  governed 
the  intellectual  life  of  the  nation, 
purely  educational  movements  being 
separated  from  it,  in  England  the 
purely  scientific  interest  has  never 
gained  the  upper  hand,  and  can 
still  complain  of  having  nowhere  a 
full  and  complete  representation. 
Around  the  writings  of  Whewell  as 
a  centre  may  be  grouped  those  of 
A.  Sedgwick  ('  A  Discourse  on  the 
Studies  of  the  University  of  Cam- 
bridge,' 1833,  5th  ed.,  1850) ;  Sir 
Wm.  Hamilton  (articles  in  the 
'  Edinburgh  Review,'  reprinted  in 
'  Discussions  on  Philosophy,  &c.,' 
1853)  ;  Sir  John  Herschel  ('A  Pre- 
liminary Discourse  on  the  Study 
of  Natural  Philosophy,'  1831)  ; 
the  criticisms  of  Lyell  ('Travels 
in  North  America,'  1845),  and  of 
the  '  Edinburgh,'  '  British  Quar- 
terly, '  and  '  Westminster '  Reviews 
('Edin.  Rev.,'  Ap.  1849,  Jan.  1874, 
'Brit.  Quart.,'  Nov.  1850,  'West. 
Rev.,'  Jan.  1855).  Whoever  desires 
to  gain  an  insight  into  the  different, 
frequently  diametrically  opposite, 
considerations  which  moulded  and 
governed  the  reconstruction  of  the 
German  university  system  on  the 
one  side,  and  on  the  other  side 
widened  in  England  the  older  ideas 
of  university  education,  should  com- 


pare the  documents  relating  to  the 
foundation  of  the  University  at 
Berlin  in  the  beginning  of  this  cen- 
tury (collected  by  Rudolf  Kopke, 
'  Die  Griindung  der  Koniglichen 
Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universitat  zu 
Berlin,'  Berlin,  1860)  with  the  writ- 
ings referred  to  in  this  note,  and 
centering  in  Whewell's  pamphlets 
and  essays.  The  personification  of 
the  German  scheme  was  Wilhelm 
von  Humboldt,  of  whom  Bockh 
said  in  his  '  Logos  epitaphios ' :  "  He 
was  a  veritable  statesman,  pene- 
trated and  led  by  ideas — a  states- 
man of  a  Periclean  greatness  of 
spirit.  Philosophy  and  poetry,  elo- 
quence, historical,  philological,  lin- 
guistic erudition,  were  fused  in 
him  into  undisturbed  harmony  and 
wonderful  symmetry."  The  re- 
forming and  revolutionary  ideas  of 
Fichte,  the  classical  ideals  of  Wolf, 
the  historical  interests  of  J.  Miiller 
the  historian,  the  literary  interests  of 
Schlegel,  the  philosophical  interests 
of  Schleiermacher,  were  combined  by 
Humboldt  into  a  realisable  scheme. 
Stein  said  of  him. in  1810  :  "  Prussia 
has  intrusted  the  management  of 
her  educational  and  scientific  in- 
stitutions to  a  man  possessed  of  a 
remarkable  intellect  and  of  great 
firmness  of  character,  and  who 
utilises  these  qualities  in  his  sphere 
of  action  with  glorious  loyalty " 
(ibid.,  pp.  61,  62). 


264  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

practical  interests  of  a  select  class  which  upheld  those 
traditions,  prevented  any  of  the  Continental  ideals,  be 
it  the  philological  of  F.  A.  Wolf,  or  the  philosophical  of 
Fichte,  or  the  scientific  of  Laplace  and  Cuvier,  from 
establishing  themselves  in  the  older  seats  of  learning. 
And  they  were,  after  all,  the  only  organisations  for  higher 
culture  which  possessed  a  historical  character  and  con- 
tinuity. Around  these  centres,  partly  in  a  friendly,  more 
frequently  in  a  hostile  spirit,  other  institutions,  other 
centres  of  culture  and  learning,  had  grown  up.  Let  us 
rapidly  survey  these  more  recent  institutions.  It  is 
hardly  necessary  again  to  mention  the  Eoyal  Society, 
which  was  an  early  offspring  of  the  older  universities,  a 
kind  of  overflow  of  the  scientific  interests  from  them  into 
si.  the  capital.  More  recent  was  the  Eoyal  Institution,  the 

The  Royal  •''••« 

institution,  creation  of  that  extraordinary  man,  Benjamin  Thompson, 
Count  Eumford.  Like  the  Eoyal  Society,  it  was  de- 
pendent upon  private  subscriptions  and  on  the  popular 
interest  created  by  its  lectures.  These  were  very  pro- 
miscuous, exhibiting  no  plan  or  unity.  In  the  early 
years  Dr  Young  and  Davy  lectured  there,  as  well  as 
Coleridge  and  Sydney  Smith.  Later  it  became  the  home 
of  Faraday,  and  through  him,  and  many  other  illustrious 
lecturers,  has  done  much  to  spread  a  taste  for  natural, 
especially  experimental,  science,  in  the  higher  and  cul- 
tivated classes.  It  has  been  a  means  of  diffusing  the 
scientific  taste,  more  perhaps  than  the  exact  scientific 
spirit,  in  the  stricter  sense  of  the  word.  Whilst  its 
lectures  may  have  kindled  in  many  a  young  listener  the 
love  of  scientific  work,  the  Institution  did  not  fulfil  the 
early  intention  of  its  founder,  nor  did  its  laboratory  play 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   ENGLAND. 


265 


the  part  of  some  of  the  great  laboratories  of  Paris  or  of 
Germany,  in  turning  out  a  large  number  of  well-trained 
experimentalists.  Davy  may  be  said  to  have  educated 
Faraday,  though  he  was  suspected  of  having  become 
jealous  of  him,  and  Faraday  declared  he  received  only 
one  valuable  suggestion  from  any  member  of  his  audience 
during  the  whole  course  of  his  lecturing.  It  is  the 
strongly  marked  individuality  of  all  these  great  men, 
expressed  in  their  persons,  their  lives,  and  their  works, 
rather  than  the  character  of  the  institution  itself,  which 
has  given  celebrity  and  historical  importance  to  the  Eoyal 
Institution.  John  Dalton's  l  position  in  the  Literary  and  32. 

Manchester 

Philosophical  Society  of  Manchester  was  similar  to  that  Literary  and 

Philosophi- 

of  Davy  and  Faraday  in  the  Eoyal  Institution ;  and  as  cal  Society- 
Faraday  can  in  some  sense  be  called  a  pupil  of  Davy,  so 
can  Prescott  Joule 2  be  termed  a  pupil  of  Dalton,  whom 


1  See  note,  p.  245. 

2  James    Prescott    Joule    (1818- 
89),  a  native  of  Salford.  "received 
from   Dalton  his  first  inducement 
to  undertake  the  work  of  an  ori- 
ginal  scientific  investigator."      He 
was  one  of  the  first  who  tried  to 
measure  electrical  action  in  terms  of 
the  units  of  well-known  mechanical 
or  chemical  changes.     His  publica- 
tions began  in  1840.    Weber's  'Elec- 
trodynamische  Maasbestimmungen,' 
that  great  monument  of  exact  meas- 
urement, wa»  published   in    1846. 
Mayer's  first  publication,  contain- 
ing a  calculation  of  the  mechanical 
equivalent  of  heat,  bears  the  date 
1842.     But  the  great  publication  of 
Gauss,  in  which  he  measures  mag- 
netic action  in  ordinary  mechanical 
(or  absolute)  units,  dates  from  1832 : 
'  Intensitas  vis  magneticse  terrestris 
ad  mensuram  absolutam  revocata' 
(Comm.  Societ.,  Gotting.,  1832,  &c.) 


Joule  in  1843  published  the  first 
of  his  accurate  determinations  of 
what  is  termed  in  physical  science 
"  J "  or  "  Joule's  equivalent  of 
heat."  He  read  successively  papers 
on  this  subject  before  the  meetings 
of  the  British  Association,  first  at 
Cork  (1843),  giving  the  constant 
"  J  "  as  838,  then  as  770,  then  as  890 
in  1845  (Brit.  Assoc.  at  Cambridge), 
lastly  at  Oxford  (1847)  as  781'5. 
From  this  meeting  dates  the  ac- 
quaintance and  scientific  co-opera- 
tion of  Joule  and  Thomson  (Lord 
Kelvin)  and  the  gradual  recognition 
of  the  importance  of  the  subject 
by  other  men  of  science  (see  Thom- 
son's address  on  Joule,  1893,  in 
'  Popular  Lectures  and  Addresses,' 
vol.  ii.  p.  558  sqq.)  Helmholtz's 
memoir,  "  Ueber  die  Erhaltung  der 
Kraft,"  which  was  theoretical — as 
Joule's  were  experimental  —  dates 
also  from  1847. 


266 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


he  succeeded  as  president  of  the  Society.  These  names 
are  identified  with  some  of  the  greatest  work  in  experi- 
mental science.  Some  of  them  may  be  said  to  be  iden- 
tified with  quite  original  theoretical  ideas  which  have 
governed  the  development  of  great  departments  of  re- 
search ever  since.  Dalton's  atomic  theory  in  chemistry, 
however,  received  a  tardy  recognition  in  England,  and 
was  firmly  established  only  by  foreign  research,  while 
Faraday's  "  lines  of  force "  remained  a  mystery  to  elec- 
tricians,1 till  William  Thomson  and  Clerk  Maxwell  made 
them  the  groundwork  of  our  most  recent  conceptions. 
It  is  well  to  note  that  neither  Young,  nor  Davy,  nor 
Faraday,  nor  Dalton,  nor  Joule  belonged  to  the  circle 
of  Cambridge  men,  and  that  probably  none  of  them  re- 
ceived any  inspiration  from  that  official  school  of  English 
mathematics.2  In  the  early  years  of  the  century  that 


1  See  Helmholtz  on  Faraday's 
ideas  in  '  Vortriige  und  Reden,'  vol. 
ii.  p.  277.  "  Since  the  mathemati- 
cal interpretation  of  Faraday's  theo- 
rems has  been  given  by  Clerk  Max- 
well in  methodically  elaborated 
scientific  formulae,  we  see,  indeed, 
how  much  definiteness  of  conception 
and  accurate  thought  were  con- 
tained in  Faraday's  words,  which 
seemed  to  his  contemporaries  so 
indefinite  aud  obscure.  And  it  is 
indeed  remarkable  in  the  highest 
degree  to  observe  how,  by  a  kind 
of  intuition,  without  using  a  single 
formula,  he  found  out  a  number  of 
comprehensive  theorems,  which  can 
only  be  strictly  proved  by  the 
highest  powers  of  mathematical 
analysis.  I  would  not  depreciate 
Faraday's  contemporaries  because 
they  did  not  recognise  this ;  I 
know  how  often  I  found  myself 
despairingly  staring  at  his  descrip- 
tions of  lines  of  force,  their  number 


and  tension,  or  looking  for  the 
meaning  of  sentences  in  which  the 
galvanic  current  is  defined  as  an 
axis  of  force,  and  similar  things. 
A  single  remarkable  discovery  can 
indeed  be  brought  about  by  a  happy 
chance, .  .  .  but  it  would  be  against 
all  rules  of  probability  that  a  numer- 
ous series  of  the  most  important 
discoveries,  such  as  Faraday  pro- 
duced, could  have  had  their  origin 
in  conceptions  which  did  not  really 
contain  a  correct,  though  perhaps 
deeply  hidden,  ground  of  truth." 
2  Young  resided  at  Cambridge  to 
take  his  medical  degree  on  his  re- 
turn from  Gottingen  ;  but  though 
his  biographer  has  inserted  a  chap- 
ter on  Cambridge  in  the  '  Life  of 
Young,'  and  though  Young's  first 
great  discovery,  that  of  the  inter- 
ferences of  waves  of  sound  and  light, 
fell  within  that  period,  there  is  no 
evidence  that  his  scientific  studies 
were  promoted  by  Cambridge  influ- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


267 


centre  had,  indeed,  to  receive  aid  from  a  still  more 
secluded  and  unacademic  quarter.  Undergraduates  of 
Cambridge  used  to  migrate  from  the  seat  of  teaching 
which  has  been  immortalised  by  Newton  to  the  remote 
Yorkshire  village  of  Sedbergh,  where  John  Dawson,1  one  33. 

John  Daw- 

of  the  few  British  analysts  who  held  their  own  against  son  of 

Sedbergh. 

the  great  foreign  authorities,  taught  the  higher  mathe- 
matics for  five  shillings  a-week. 

During  the  latter  part  of  the  eighteenth  century  a 
formidable  rival  to  the  learning  of  Oxford  and  Cambridge 
had  sprung  up  in  the  Scotch  universities.  These  were  34. 

teaching  centres,  more  after  the  manner  of  the  foreign  univer- 
sities. 
universities.     They  had  been  started  on  the  model  of  the 

University  of  Paris  or  of  the  older  Italian  universities ; 
some  had  their  origin  in  the  educational  movement  which, 
especially  in  those  countries  where  the  doctrines  of  Calvin 
prevailed,  accompanied  the  Eeformation.2  All  through  the 


ences ;  in  fact  he  makes  a  disparaging 
remark  regardingBritish  as  compared 
with  Continental  mathematics.  See 
Peacock's  'Life  of  Dr  Young,'  p.  127. 
1  John  Dawson  (1734-1820),  the 
8on  of  a  poor  "  statesman  "  of  Gars- 
dale,  tended  his  father's  sheep  till 
he  was  twenty.  He  studied  mathe- 
matics with  innate  love  and  ability, 
inventing  a  system  of  conic  sec- 
tions out  of  his  own  brain.  By 
teaching  he  gained  a  little  money. 
In  1756  he  instructed  three  young 
men — of  whom  Adam  Sedgwick's 
father  was  one — before  they  went 
up  for  their  Cambridge  studies.  He 
then  became  assistant  to  a  surgeon 
at  Lancaster.  Having  saved  £100 
he  walked  to  Edinburgh  and  studied 
medicine  there.  His  funds  spent, 
he  returned  to  Sedbergh,  where  he 
practised  as  a  surgeon.  When  he 
had  saved  a  larger  sum  he  proceeded 


with  this  to  London.  After  tak- 
ing his  degree  in  1767,  he  settled 
in  his  native  county  to  practise  his 
profession  and  teach  the  higher 
mathematics  to  Cambridge  under- 
graduates. They  nocked  to  him 
in  the  summer,  and  between  1781 
and  1794  he  numbered  eight  senior 
wranglers  among  his  pupils.  In 
1797  and  subsequent  years  he 
counted  four  more.  In  1812  he 
ceased  teaching.  He  wrote  papers 
on  the  "  precession  "  and  the  lunar 
theory,  and  followed  the  develop- 
ment of  higher  mathematics  on  the 
Continent.  See  '  Life  and  letters 
of  Adam  Sedgwick,'  by  J.  W. 
Clark  and  T.  M'K.  Hughes,  1890, 
vol.  i.  p.  61,  &c. 

2  Details  referring  to  the  founda- 
tion of  the  Scotch  universities  are 
given  by  Sir  A.  Grant  in  the  first 
volume  of  his  '  Story  of  the  Univer- 


268 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


seventeenth  and  eighteenth  centuries  they  stood  in  inti- 
'mate  relations  with  such  Continental  centres  of  study  as 
Paris,  Geneva,  and  the  Dutch  universities.  Adam  Smith 
and  David  Hume  were  in  direct  and  very  intimate  inter- 
course with  French  thought,  the  former  having  obtained  in 
France  a  knowledge  of  the  no veL views  of  the  great  politi- 
cal economists  of  the  pre-revolutionary  period.  Edinburgh 
became  in  the  first  half  of  the  last  century,  under  the 
influence  of  John  Monro  and  his  son  Alexander  (1697- 
1767),  who  was  a  pupil  of  Boerhaave,  a  medical  school 
of  great  importance,  rivalling  London  in  its  foreign  rep- 


sity  of  Edinburgh,'  2  vols.,  1884. 
Three  of  them — St  Andrews,  Glas- 
gow, and  Aberdeen — were  founded 
in  the  century  preceding  the  Re- 
formation ;  St  Andrews  about 
1411  by  Bishop  Wardlaw,  because 
Scotch  students  had  been  un- 
popular and  "  molested "  at  Ox- 
ford. The  University  of  Glasgow 
was  founded  in  1450,  reference 
being  made  to  the  University  of 
Bologna  in  the  Bull  of  Pope  Nicholas 

V.  ;  but  it  has  also  been  observed 
that    ' '  the  customs  and   technical 
phraseology  showed  an  imitation  of 
the    institutes    of    Louvain,    then 
and   for  all  the  following  century 
the  model  university  of  Northern 
Europe,    of    which    a    Scotchman, 
John   Lichton,  had   been   Rector" 
(p.  21).      Aberdeen  was  started  by 
Bishop  Elphinstone,  who  had  studied 
in  Glasgow  and  Paris,  and  been  pro- 
fessor, both  there  and  at  Orleans,  of 
canon  and  civil  law.      In  the  pre- 
amble to  the  Bull  of  Pope  Alexander 

VI.  the  Universities  of   Paris  and 
Bologna    are    referred   to   (p.    29). 
But   th«   universities  seem  not  to 
have  flourished  previous  to  the  Refor- 
mation, when  they  were  "  purged  " 
and  a  new  spirit  and  order  infused 
into  them.    St  Andrews  was  to  have 
four  faculties,  named  as  in  foreign 


universities — Philosophy,  Medicine, 
Law,  and  Divinity  (p.  63).  Glas- 
gow and  Aberdeen  were  to  have 
two  faculties,  of  which  the  first 
was  to  be  Philosophy  (or  Arts), 
the  second  to  comprise  Law  and 
Divinity.  The  '  Book  of  Discipline ' 
contained  a  very  complete  scheme 
of  higher  graded  education  ;  but 
this  was  only  gradually  and  par- 
tially realised ;  secondary  schools 
being  wanting,  the  "  colleges  "  had 
to  descend  to  elementary  teaching 
(p.  67).  A  jealousy  also  existed  on 
the  part  of  those  in  power  regard- 
ing the  older  universities,  these 
being — as  the  King  of  France  de- 
clared when  refusing  to  grant  to 
the  Academy  of  Geneva  the  rights 
of  a  university — hotbeds  of  heresy 
(p.  125).  Accordingly  the  latest 
academic  creation  in  Scotland  was 
the  foundation  by  the  "Town 
Council  and  ministers  of  the  city  " 
of  the  College  of  Edinburgh  (pp. 
99,  121,  127)  between  the  years 
1561  and  1578,  King  James's  char- 
ter dating  from  14th  April  1582. 
"But  it  did  not,  like  the  older  uni- 
versities, commence  with  a  blaze 
of  success  and  then  collapse.  It 
started  from  a  humble  beginning 
and  steadily  expanded  into  greater 
things"  (p.  158). 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


269 


35. 

The  Royal 


utation.1  Edinburgh  had'  also  one  of  the  earliest  chairs 
of  chemistry.  It  grew  into  an  independent  centre  of 
original  scientific  work  when  in  1783  the  Eoyal  Society  E  ^  h 
of  Edinburgh  was  incorporated.  Ever  since  the  founda- 
tion of  the  Scotch  universities,  mathematics  had  been 
studied  independently,  in  Scotland,  where  John  Napier 
of  Merchiston  had  at  the  end  of  the  sixteenth  century 
invented  logarithms.  "  "Whether  we  consider  the  great 
originality  of  the  idea,  the  difficulty  of  carrying  it  into 
effect  in  the  state  in  which  algebraical  analysis  then  was, 
or  the  immense  practical  and  theoretical  value  of  the  inven- 
tion, we  shall  have  little  difficulty  in  claiming  for  Napier 
the  honour  of  a  discovery  unsurpassed  in  brilliancy  in 
the  whole  history  of  mathematics." 2  From  that  time  the 


1  "  In  1738  the  foundation-stone 
of  that  building  which  was  till  re- 
cently the  Royal  Infirmary  of  Edin- 
burgh was  laid,  and  a  great  public 
enthusiasm  on  the  subject  was  mani- 
fested.     Drummond,  the  greatest 
/Edile  that  has  ever  governed  the 
city  of  Edinburgh,  and  Monro,  were 
appointed  the  Building  Committee, 
and  they  paid  the  workmen  with 
their  own  hands.     All  classes  con- 
tributed :   landowners  gave  stone ; 
merchants    gave   timber  ;    farmers 
lent    their    carts    for    carriage    of 
materials ;    even   the    masons   and 
other  labourers  gave  one  day's  work 
out  of  the  month  gratis,  as  it  was  a 
building  for  the  benefit  of  the  poor  " 
(Sir  A.   Grant,  loc.   cit.,  vol.  i.  p. 
306). 

2  Quoted  by  Sir  A.   Grant  (loc. 
cit.,  vol.  ii.  p.  293)  from  Chrystal's 
unpublished     Inaugural     Address, 
'  John  Napier,  Baron  of  Merchiston ' 
(1550-1617).     The  'Mirifici  Logar- 
ithmorum  Canonis  Descriptio '  ap- 
peared in  1614.     The  'Logarithmo- 
rum  Chilias  prima '  of  Henry  Briggs 


(1556-1630),  professor  at  Oxford, 
contains  the  first  table  of  com- 
mon or  decimal  logarithms. 
Kepler  (1571-1630)  received  the 
invention  with  great  enthusiasm  as 
of  immense  importance  to  astro- 
nomy. "The  more  one  considers 
the  condition  of  science  at  the  time, 
and  the  state  of  the  country  in 
which  the  discovery  took  place, 
the  more  wonderful  does  the  in- 
vention of  logarithms  appear.  .  .  . 
It  is  one  of  the  surprises  in  the 
history  of  science  that  logarithms 
were  invented  as  an  arithmetical 
improvement  years  before  their 
connection  with  exponents  was 
known.  It  is  to  be  noticed  also 
that  the  invention  was  not  the  re- 
sult of  any  happy  accident.  Every- 
thing tends  to  show  that  it  was 
the  result  of  many  years  of  labour 
and  thought  undertaken  with  this 
special  object ;  Napier  succeeded  in 
devising,  by  the  help  of  arithmetic 
and  geometry  alone,  the  one  great 
simplification  of  which  they  were 
susceptible  —  a  simplification  to 


270 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


36. 

The  '  Edin- 
burgh 
Review.' 


science  was  cultivated  at  the  different  Scotch  universities, 
which  supplied  Oxford  with  a  Professor  of  Astronomy 
(preferred  to  Halley),  in  the  person  of  David  Gregory. 
"  David  Gregory  not  only  introduced  the  '  Principia '  to 
Edinburgh  students,  but  he  also  brought  them  to  the 
notice  of  Englishmen."  J  The  Philosophical  (afterwards 
called  the  Eoyal)  Society  of  Edinburgh  was  much  in- 
debted to  Colin  Maclaurin,2  who  almost  alone  with  Landen 
and  Ivory  maintained  the  reputation  of  British  mathe- 
maticians during  seventy  years,  whilst  the  Continental 
school  was  revolutionising  that  science.  A  successor  to 
Maclaurin  in  the  mathematical  chair  at  Edinburgh,  John 
Play  fair,3  introduced  the  Continental  methods  into  the 
studies  of  the  Scotch  universities  about  the  end  of  the 
last  century.  He  was  one  of  the  early  contributors  to 
the  '  Edinburgh  Eeview,'  which  in  politics,  literature, 
and  science  inaugurated  a  new  kind  of  criticism,  and  led 
a  powerful  attack  upon  all  those  traditional  forms  of 
government,  taste,  and  learning  which  prevented  the  free 
expansion  of  ideas  and  the  progress  of  science  and  prac- 
tical interests.  Though  not  always  judiciously  used,  the 


which  the  following  two  hundred 
and  eighty  years  have  added  no- 
thing" (Glaisher  in  '  Ency.  Brit.,' 
9th  ed.,  article  "Napier"). 

1  David  Gregory  (1661-1708)  has 
"  the  honour  of  having  been  the 
first  to  give  public  lectures  on  the 
Newtonian  philosophy.  This  he  did 
in  Edinburgh  five-and-thirty  years 
before  these  doctrines  were  accepted 
as  part  of  the  public  instruction  in 
the  university  of  their  inventor" 
(Sir  A.  Grant  and  Chrystal,  loc. 
cit.,  vol.  ii.  p.  296).  Cambridge 
writers,  headed  by  Whewell,  are 
loath  to  admit  any  reluctance  on 


the  part  of  their  university  in  ac- 
cepting the  Newtonian  philosophy, 
in  spite  of  Whiston's  testimony  to 
the  contrary.  See  on  this  Whewell's 
'  History  of  the  Inductive  Sciences,' 
3rd  ed.,  vol.  ii.  p.  149,  &c. 

2  Colin    Maclaurin    (1698-1746) 
published,     1742,    a    '  Treatise    on 
Fluxions,'  2  vols.  4to.     In  1740  he 
shared  with  Daniel  Bernoulli  and 
Euler  the  prize  of  the  French  Aca- 
demy for  his  '  Essay  on  the  Tides. ' 

3  John  Playfair  (1748-1819)  was 
Professor  of  Mathematics  and  then, 
(from  1805)  of  Natural  Philosophy. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND.          271 

influence  of  that  review  must  have  been  very  powerful 
in  rousing  the  older  English  universities  out  of  a  state 
of  stagnation,  and  especially  in  stimulating  younger  minds 
in  the  direction  of  the  long-delayed  reform  of  studies. 
An  important  step  in  this  direction  was  taken  by  three  37. 

The  Analy- 

undergraduates  of  Cambridge — Herschel,  Babbage,  and  ticai  society 
Peacock — who  in  1812  formed  the  Analytical  Society,  brid8e- 
with  the  distinct  object  of  introducing  the  more  modern 
and  powerful  analytical  methods  developed  mainly  by 
Euler  and  Lagrange,  and  deposited  in  their  numerous 
Memoirs  in  the  publications  of  the  foreign  academies.1 
In  harmony  with  them  worked  Whewell,  Airy,  and 
Sedgwick,  who  did  much  to  enlarge  the  programme  of 
mathematical  and  scientific  studies,  though  they  very 
staunchly  upheld  that  the  real  object  of  university 
education  could  not  be  identified  with  any  special 
method  or  school  of  thought,  but  was  expressed  in 
the  specific  ideal  peculiar  to  England,  that  of  a  liberal 
education.2 

The  universities  of  Scotland,  unlike  those  of  England,        ss. 

University 

instead  of  nursing  an  exclusive  spirit,  and  encouraging  lifein 

0  Scotland. 

only  scanty  intercourse  between  teachers  and  students  of 
different  centres,  lived  in  constant  exchange  of  professors 
and  ideas — much  in  the  same  way  as  has  always  been  the 
custom  on  a  larger  scale  among  German  and  other  Conti- 
nental universities.  Though  this  is  destructive  of  that 
individual  character  of  the  university  or  the  college  which 


1  See  note  1  to  p.  233 ;  also  for 
many  details  Rouse  Ball's  '  History 
of  the   Study   of  Mathematics  at 
Cambridge,'  1889,  p.   120,  &c. 

2  On  Whewell  and  his  writings 
on   university    education   see  note 


to  p.  261.  Sir  George  Biddell 
Airy  (1801-1891)  published  in  1826 
'Mathematical  Tracts'  (2nd  ed., 
1831)  on  the  lunar  and  planetary 
theories,  &c.,  for  the  use  of  students 
in  the  university. 


272 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


is  so  highly  prized  by  many  English  fellows,  it  is  certainly 
more  conducive  to  the  progress  of  studies  and  of  research, 
and  it  is  the  cause  why  in  the  early  history  of  recent 
science  the  universities  of  Scotland  have  played  so  much 
more  important  a  part  than  those  of  England.  Whilst  in 
England  modern  science  was  cultivated  outside  the  pale 
of  the  universities  by  Priestley,  Davy,  Wollaston,  Young, 
Dalton,  Faraday,  and  Joule,  to  whom  we  may  even  add 
Green  and  Boole,  all  eminent  Scotch  men  of  science,  such 
as  Gregory,  Simson,  Maclaurin,  Playfair,  Black,  Thomson, 
Leslie,  Brewster,  and  Forbes,  were  university  professors, 
many  of  whom  did  not  confine  their  labours  to  one  centre, 
but  spread  the  light  of  their  ideas  and  researches  all  over 
the  country.1  Whilst  England  has  been  great  in  single 
names,  Scotland  has  certainly  in  proportion  done  more 


1  Napier  of  Merchiston  remained 
outside  the  pale  of  the  universities. 
At  that  time  the  College  of  Edin- 
burgh had  no  mathematical  pro- 
fessor ;  but  Glasgow  had,  and  so 
had  Aberdeen.  James  Gregory  was 
educated  at  Aberdeen,  was  then  pro- 
fessor at  St  Andrews,  and  subse- 
quently at  Edinburgh.  Colin  Mac- 
laurin was  educated  at  Glasgow, 
then  professor  at  Aberdeen  and  at 
Edinburgh.  Playfair  was  educated 
at  St  Andrews,  and  lectured  there 
before  coming  to  Edinburgh.  Leslie 
was  trained  at  St  Andrews,  and  was 
then  professor  first  of  mathematics 
and  after  wards  of  natural  philosophy 
at  Edinburgh.  Black  was  educated 
at  Glasgow  and  Edinburgh,  and 
was  professor  at  both  universities. 
Brewster  studied  at  Edinburgh,  and 
was  subsequently  principal  of  St 
Andrews  and  then  of  Edinburgh. 
Forbes,  as  student  and  professor,  be- 
longs exclusively  to  Edinburgh,  and 
so  did  in  earlier  times  Robert  Sim- 


son,  the  great  mathematical  pro- 
fessor. Adam  Smith  belongs  exclu- 
sively to  Glasgow,  though  he  had 
lectured  in  Edinburgh  before  he 
was  appointed  professor  at  Glasgow. 
But  the  contrast  between  England 
and  Scotland  becomes  still  more 
prominent  if  we  look  at  the  medi- 
cal sciences  and  note  the  great 
array  of  celebrated  professors  at 
Edinburgh,  Culleu,  Brown,  Gregory, 
Alison,  Hamilton,  Syme,  Simpson, 
Christison,  and  Charles  Bell,  where- 
as the  equally  great  names  of  John 
and  William  Hunter,  of  Jenner,  of 
Astley  Cooper  and  Bright,  have  no 
connection  with  the  English  univer- 
sities ;  Sydenham  was  only  slightly 
connected  with  Oxford  and  Cam- 
bridge, and  even  Harvey  never 
occupied  a  prominent  position  at 
Oxford.  Through  situation  or  con- 
stitution the  English  universities 
were  unable  to  open  a  field  of  ac- 
tivity for  these  celebrated  men. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


273 


to  diffuse  modern  scientific  knowledge.  The  great  pub- 
lishing firms  of  Edinburgh  have  also  for  more  than  a 
century  done  much  through  Cyclopaedias,  Eeviews,  and 
Magazines  to  spread  general  information  of  all  kinds ;  * 
whilst  Hume,  Adam  Smith,  and  the  subsequent  Scotch 
school  of  metaphysicians  have  exerted  their  influence 
during  the  whole  of  this  century,  not  only  in  Great 
Britain,  but  over  the  whole  of  Europe.2  In  the  more 
circumscribed  domain  of  scientific  thought  a  powerful 
influence  has  again  been  exerted  from  Scotland  as  a 
centre,  and  through  the  larger  instrumentality  of  the 
University  of  Cambridge,  on  the  study  of  mathematical 
and  experimental  physics,  and  what  we  may  term  the 
spirit  and  method  of  these  sciences.  This  influence  be- 


1  The  most  popular  Cyclopaedia, 
that  of  Chambers,  had  its  origin  in 
Edinburgh  in  1860.  It  was  founded 
on  the  tenth  edition  of  Brockhaus's 
'  Conversations-Lexicon.'  The  more 
important  '  Encyclopaedia  Britan- 
nica '  was  published  there  also  in 
1771,  3  vols. ;  2nd  ed.,  1777.  The 
'  Edinburgh  Review '  was  estab- 
lished in  1802  by  Jeffrey,  Scott, 
Homer,  Brougham,  and  Sydney 
Smith  ;  it  was  the  first  successful 
"  Quarterly,"  carried  011  independ- 
ently of  the  booksellers,  after 
several  unsuccessful  attempts  had 
been  made  in  a  similar  direction  by 
Adam  Smith  and  Hugh  Blair  in 
1755,  and  after  Gilbert  Stuart  and 
William  Smellie  had  issued  from 
1773  to  1775  the  '  Edinburgh  Mag- 
azine and  Review.'  No  such  peri- 
odical ever  attained  to  the  circula- 
tion of  the  '  Edinburgh  Review,'  of 
which  at  one  time  20,000  copies 
were  sold.  The  first  high -class 
monthly  Magazine  was  also  printed 
in  Edinburgh  by  Blackwood  in 
1817,  with  Scott,  Lockhart,  Hogg, 

VOL.  I. 


Maginn,  Syme,  and  John  Wilson  as 
contributors.  '  Tait's  Edinburgh 
Magazine*  was  the  first  shilling 
magazine.  The  brothers  William 
and  Robert  Chambers,  in  1832, 
started  the  Journal  named  after 
them.  They  also  brought  out  many 
popular  works  of  sterling  merit, 
mostly  written  by  Robert  Cham- 
bers, than  whom  none  did  more  to 
introduce  a  knowledge  of  nature 
into  popular  reading,  and  to  give  a 
healthy  tone  and  moral  influence 
to  the  cheap  literature  which  has 
become  such  an  important  factor 
in  modern  culture. 

2  Whilst  Locke  exercised  the 
greatest  influence  on  French  phil- 
osophy, Kant  starts  more  directly 
from  Hume.  The  literature  of  the 
Restoration  in  France  again  at- 
taches itself  to  the  Scotch  meta- 
physicians, notably  Reid.  It  is 
interesting  that  both  Kant  and 
the  greatest  representative  of  the 
French  "Ideology,"  De  Tracy,  were 
of  Scotch  descent. 


8 


274  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

longs  to  the  second  half  of  the  century,  and  is  centred  in 
the  two  names  of  William  Thomson  (Lord  Kelvin)  and 
James  Clerk  Maxwell,  who  may  be  said  to  have  jointly 
revolutionised  natural  philosophy.  It  began  with  the  ap- 
pearance of  George  Stokes's  and  William  Thomson's  im- 
portant contributions  to  mathematical  physics,  and  with 
the  publication  of  that  suggestive  and  stimulating — but 
unfortunately  unfinished — work  by  Thomson  and  Tait  on 
Natural  Philosophy.  It  was  represented  to  the  fullest 
extent  in  Clerk  Maxwell's  activity  in  the  Cavendish 
Laboratory  at  Cambridge.  But  the  consideration  of  this 
subject  belongs  to  a  later  chapter  of  the  present  work, 
and  is  only  mentioned  here  in  connection  with  the  intel- 
lectual intercourse  and  exchange  which  has  existed  all 
through  this  century  between  the  invigorating  spirit  of  the 
north  and  the  more  conservative  spirit  of  the  southern 
39.  portion  of  the  island.  Besides  Scotland  another  centre 
ifathemati-  — the  Dublin  School — has  gained  European  renown 

cal  School. 

through  a  series  of  mathematical  labours  of  the  highest 
importance,  some  of  them  of  an  originality  hardly  yet 
sufficiently  recognised.  This  school  is  represented  by 
the  names  of  Rowan  Hamilton,1  MacCullagh,  Sal- 

1  Of  Rowan  Hamilton's  dynami-  ;  maticians  who,  like  Gauss,  led  the 
cal  "  principle  of  varying  action  "  I  way  into  new  channels  of  thought 
I  have  spoken  in  a  note  to  p.  231.  |  and  succeeded  in  breaking  through 
William  Rowan  Hamilton  (1805-65)  ]  the  traditional  forms  of  this  science, 
cannot  with  the  same  certainty  as  j  which  more  than  any  other  is  ham- 
Kant  and  De  Tracy  be  claimed  as  ,  pered  in  its  development  by  trans- 
of  Scotch  descent.  Indeed  he  mitted  customs  and  habits  of  repre- 
seems  to  belong  distinctly  to  Ire-  '  sentation.  Thus,  after  ten  years  of 
land.  See  Tait's  article  in  the  !  research  and  thought  in  connection 
'  Xorth  British  Review,'  September  with  the  representation  of  extend- 
1866,  and  Perceval  Graves's  reply  in  ed  algebraical  forms  by  means  of 
'Life  of  W.  R.  Hamilton'  (3  vols.,  I  the  different  directions  in  space,  he 
1882-89,  vol.  i.  p.  5).  He  was  one  !  succeeded  in  establishing  the  fun- 
of  the  few  quite  original  mathe-  damental  principle  of  his  theory  of 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIKIT   IN    ENGLAND. 


275 


mon ;  nor  should  we  forget  the  suggestive  writings  of 
George  Boole.2  The  influence  of  these  men  originated 
outside  of  Cambridge,  and  a  history  of  mathematics  at 
that  university  does  not  contain  their  names,3  though  the 
ideas  of  which  they  have  been  the  bearers  have  largely 
entered  into  the  text-books  and  the  teaching  of  the  Cam- 
bridge school. 

So  far  I  have  mainly  dealt  with  one  side  only  on  which 
the  progress  of  science  depends,  namely,  the  methodical 
use  of  experiment,  measurement,  and  calculation :  this 


quaternions  —  complex  quantities 
which  are  compounded  of  a  purely 
algebraical  or  quantitative  element 
and  three  distinct  elements  corre- 
sponding to  the  three  directions  or 
dimensions  of  space.  He  was  the 
first  to  work  out  this  calculus,  and 
the  labour  occupied  twenty  years 
of  his  life.  In  Hamilton's  calculus 
of  quaternions,  distance  (or  length) 
and  direction  are  introduced  as  they 
naturally  present  themselves  when 
we  deal  with  geometrical  or  physical 
problems,  instead  of  all  quantities 
being  reduced  to  lengths,  as  was 
the  case  in  the  Cartesian  geometry. 
Hamilton  thus  broke  through  the 
conventionalism  of  the  latter  and 
showed  how  the  consideration  of  di- 
rections in  space  forces  us  to  extend 
the  original  operations  of  arithmetic. 
It  is  interesting  to  note  how  simul- 
taneously Grassmann  (see  p.  243, 
note  1 )  in  his  '  Ausdehnungslehre ' 
(1844)  and  Von  Staudt  in  his  '  Geo- 
metrie  der  Lage'  (1847),  quite  inde- 
pendently worked  at  similar  exten- 
sions of  our  arithmetical  and  geo- 
metrical conceptions,  and  how  sub- 
sequently quaternions,  in  which 
Hamilton  had  seen  a  powerful  me- 
thod for  solving  geometrical  and 
physical  problems,  present  them- 
selves as  a  special  form  of  the  ex- 
tended algebra  and  geometry  elabor- 


ated from  these  different  beginnings. 
Whilst  the  practical  usefulness  of 
the  calculus  has  been  demonstrated 
by  some  extensive  applications,  as, 
for  example,  to  spherical  trigono- 
metry, the  ideas  contained  in  it — 
frequently  without  Hamilton's  no- 
tation— are  gradually  finding  their 
way  into  text-books,  and  the  strange- 
ness which  for  half  a  century  pre- 
vented the  labours  of  Hamilton, 
Grassmann,  and  Von  Staudt  from 
being  generally  appreciated,  is  dis- 
appearing. A  popular  exposition 
of  the  relation  of  quaternions  to 
general  arithmetic  is  given  in  0. 
Stolz,  'Grossenund  Zahlen,'  Leip- 
zig, Teubner,  1891. 

1  The  excellent  treatises  of  Sal- 
mon on  'Higher  Algebra,'  'Higher 
Plane  Curves, '  '  Geometry  of  Three 
Dimensions,'  and  '  Conic  Sections ' 
have  in  their  German  translations 
by  Fiedler  done  a  great  work   in 
systematising  and  popularising  mo- 
dern  conceptions    in    algebra    and 
geometry.    See  Gino  Loria's  treatise 
on  the  "  Principle  Theories  of  Geo- 
metry "  in  the  German  translation 
by  Schutte,  Leipzig,   1888,    p.  25, 
&c. 

2  See  p.  247,  note  2. 

8  See  Rouse  Ball,  '  A  History  of 
the  Study  of  Mathematics  at  Cam- 
bridge,'  1889. 


276  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

side  had  been  very  largely  developed  by  the  great  French 
naturalists  and  mathematicians  in  the  beginning  of  our 
period.  The  change  in  the  higher  branches  of  science 
which  took  place  during  the  first  half  of  the  century  is 
greatly  owing  to  them,  and  to  the  later  German  school, 

40.  which  was  much  influenced  by  them.     If  we  compare 

ofBritish36  the  contributions  of  British  science  in  these  branches, 
contribu- 
tions to       they  are  indeed  inferior  in  bulk,  and  still  more  so  in 

science. 

methodical  arrangement;  but  among  them  is  a  small 
number  of  works  of  the  first  order,  which  are  embodi- 
ments of  scientific  ideas  of  the  very  highest  importance. 
Introduced  into  the  great  edifice  of  scientific  research 
which  was  being  planned  and  erected  on  the  Continent, 
they  mark  the  very  corner-stones  of  the  building,  stand- 
ing out  in  bold  and  conspicuous  prominence.  But  it  is 
a  fact  that  no  Academy  existed  in  this  country  which 
was  zealous  in  collecting  and  arranging  all  the  best 
labours  of  scattered  philosophers,  no  university  which 
was  anxious  to  attract  and  train  promising  intellects, 
no  comprehensive  text-books  and  hand-books,  ensuring 
right  guidance,  correctness  of  knowledge,  and  complete- 
ness of  study,  no  historical  and  philosophical  traditions 
guaranteeing  that  novel  contributions  should  make  their 
appearance  under  favourable  conditions,  or  supplying  the 
most  appropriate  mise  en  sctne  for  new  ideas. 

41.  It  is  the  French  Institute,  in  the  earlier  years  of  the 
scientific      century,   and   the   German   university  system,   with  its 

knowledge 

on  the         many  local  ramifications  and  literary  organs,  during  the 

Continent. 

whole  of  the  century,  which  have  done  the  great  work 
of  systematising  and  diffusing  scientific  knowledge,  and 
of  introducing  the  exact  spirit  of  research.  There  is 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIKIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


277 


something  casual  and  accidental  about  the  great  ideas 
which  British  men  of  science  contributed  during  the  first 
half  of  the  century.  Each  of  them  chooses  an  isolated  42. 

Isolation  of 

position,  a  special  form  of  delivery,  frequently  a  Ian- 
guage  and  style  of  his  own.  They  attach  little  or  no 
importance  to  the  labours  of  others,  with  which  they 
are  frequently  unacquainted.1  Important  papers  are 
lost  or  buried,  as  in  the  case  of  Cavendish  and  Green. 
Novel  ideas  are  communicated  in  unintelligible  language 
and  symbols,  and  accordingly  neglected.  This  was  the 
case  with  Dr  Young's  writings,  and  to  a  certain  extent 
with  Faraday's.  The  greatest  discoveries  were  unduly 
postponed  through  the  absence  of  assistance,  as  seems  to 
have  been  the  case  with  Adams's  discovery  of  Neptune,2 
perhaps  with  Stokes's  anticipation  of  spectrum  analysis.3 


1  This  is  correct  of  most  of  the 
great  men  referred  to  in  the  course 
of  this  chapter.    Among  them,  how- 
ever, Rowan  Hamilton  forms  an  ex- 
ception.    Though  working  on  quite 
original  lines,  he  took  a  great  in- 
terest in  the  labours  and  sugges- 
tions contained  in  the  writings  of 
his  forerunners  and  contemporaries, 
as  the  historical  notices  in  the  pre- 
face to  his  '  Lectures  on    Quater- 
nions'  (1853)  prove;    likewise  his 
correspondence  with  De  Morgan  (see 
'  Life  of  Sir  W.  R.  H.,'  vol.  iii.) 

2  The  story  of  the  discovery  of 
Neptune  has  been  frequently  told. 
The   first   publication   of    the   ele- 
ments   of    the    suspected    planet, 
which  enabled  a  search  to  be  made, 
came  from  Leverrier  to  the  Paris 
Academy   of    Sciences   on   the   1st 
July  and   the   31st   August   1846. 
In  consequence  of  this  publication, 
Galle  at  Berlin,  requested  by  Lever- 
rier to  search  in  the  neighbourhood 
of  S  Capricorni,  and  comparing  his 
observations    made    on    the    same 


night  on  which  he  received  the 
request,  23rd  September  1846,  with 
Bremiker's  map,  actually  found  the 
planet.  Subsequently  it  became 
known  that  Adams  of  Cambridge 
had  already  communicated  his 
elements  in  September  and  October 
1845  to  Challis  and  Airy,  and  that 
the  former  had  actually  seen  the 
planet  on  the  4th  and  12th  of 
August  1846,  but  —  for  want  of 
equally  detailed  maps  —  had  not 
compared  the  observation  and  estab- 
lished the  discovery.  See  Whewell's 
'  History  of  the  Inductive  Sciences,' 
third  ed.,  1857,  vol.  ii.  p.  460,  &c. ; 
also  Wolf,  '  Geschichte  der  Astro- 
nomic,' p.  537,  &c. 

8  It  appears  from  a  communica- 
tion of  Sir  William  Thomson  (Lord 
Kelvin)  to  Kirchhoff  immediately 
after  the  latter  had  published  in 
1859  his  explanation  of  the  iden- 
tity of  the  dark  lines  in  the  solar 
spectrum  with  the  bright  lines  in 
the  spectra  of  coloured  flames,  that 
Stokes,  soon  after  the  publication 


278 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


What  might  not  these  great  minds  have  accomplished  had 
they  attached  the  same  importance  to  style  and  form  as 
most  of  the  great  French  men  of  science,  or  had  they  been 
called  upon  to  teach  a  number  of  eager  pupils,  anxious, 
not  to  take  honours  and  degrees,  but  to  understand  and 
further  elaborate  the  suggestions  of  their  masters,  as  has 
been  the  custom  and  tradition  in  Germany  ?  The  history 
of  English  science  during  the  first  half  of  the  century 
consists  of  a  series  of  biographies,  or  of  monographs  on 
single  ideas  and  points  of  vi^w.  "We  are  struck  by  the 
individual  greatness  of  the  minds  which  produced  them, 
their  originality  or  the  suddenness  of  their  appearance. 
An  doge  by  the  permanent  secretary  of  the  Academy  has 
usually  been  considered  sufficient  to  satisfy  the  historian 
of  science  in  France ;  the  life  of  every  great  philosopher 
in  Germany  is  identical  with  the  history  of  a  phase  of 
thought  or  with  a  school  of  research :  in  England  alone 
the  person  of  the  thinker  has  nearly  always  claimed  the 


by  Miller  in  1845  and  by  Foucault 
in  1849  of  observations  relating  to 
this  subject,  had  suggested  in  the 
course  of  conversation  that  there  is 
a  correspondence  between  emission 
and  absorption  of  the  same  kind  of 
light  by  the  vibrating  molecules  of 
the  same  body,  according  as  it  is 
used  as  a  source  or  a  screen  for 
light  Had  this  idea  of  Stokes's, 
which  suggested  the  presence  of 
sodium  in  the  atmosphere  of  the 
sun,  been  followed  out  at  the  time, 
the  discovery  of  spectrum  analysis 
would  have  taken  place  ten  years 
earlier.  Actually,  the  various  pub- 
lications, beginning  with  Fraun- 
hofer's  description  of  the  dark  lines 
in  the  solar  spectrum  in  1814  and 
proceeding  through  the  observa- 
tions of  Herschel,  Talbot,  Drum- 


mond,  Miller,  Angstrom,  Pliicker, 
Swan,  and  Balfour  Stewart  on 
the  absorption  and  radiation  of 
heat,  found  their  consummation 
when  Bunsen  and  Kirchhoff  settled 
the  main  point  in  question — vi:., 
"  that  the  bright  lines  of  an  in- 
candescent gaseous  body  depend  on 
the  chemical  constituents  of  the 
same."  Then  at  length  spectrum 
analysis  became  possible.  See  on 
this  matter  Kirchhoff  rs  own  histori- 
cal rtsumt  of  the  year  1862,  re- 
printed in  'Gesarnmelte  Abhand- 
lungen'  (Leipzig,  1882),  p.  625, 
&c.  ;  also  Sir  William  Thomson's 
'  Baltimore  Lectures,'  shorthand 
notes,  1884,  p.  100,  and  Stokes's 
translation  of  Kirchhoff 's  first  paper 
in  1860  ('Philo*.  Magazine,'  March 
1860). 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


279 


greater  share  of  popular  attention.1  His  mental  labours 
have  preserved  an  individual  character,  shutting  them 
out  during  his  life  from  common  contact,  and  limiting 
their  fertilising  power,  like  that  of  an  oasis  in  the  desert, 
to  a  narrow  circle  of  casual  visitors.  Minds  like  Newton 
and  Faraday,  full  of  new  life,  but  modestly  content  with 
deepening  and  strengthening  their  secluded  vigour,  re- 
frained from  boastful  publicity  or  ostentatious  parade, 
working  for  all  ages  rather  than  for  a  special  school  or  a 

passing  generation.     It  is  the  individualism  of  the  English       43. 

individual- 
character,  the  self-reliant  strength  of  natural  genius,  which  |m°f  *he 

comes  out  most  strongly  in  its  great  examples  of  scientific  character- 
work.     In  characters  of  smaller  breadth,  in  intellects  of 
lesser  power,  these  tendencies  show  themselves  in  ways 
which  we  cannot   always  admire   or   commend :  in  the 
emulation  for  place  and  position,  in  the  competing  for 


1  This  explains  the  remarkable 
richness  of  English  literature  in 
biographies,  containing  copious  col- 
lections of  correspondence,  and  the 
.almost  total  absence  of  such  litera- 
ture in  France,*which,  on  the  other 
•side,  is  rich  in  memoirs,  written  by 
•statesmen  and  authors  themselves. 
As  the  students  of  nature  have 
usually  little  time  for  autobio- 
•graphy,  we  possess  of  the  long  list 
•of  great  names  in  modern  French 
•science  hardly  any  personal  records 
-such  as  are  so  plentiful  in  English 
literature.  What  we  miss  in  many 
•of  these  elaborate  and  frequently 
gossiping  narratives  is  a  just  ap- 
preciation of  the  position  of  the 
•subject  of  the  Tbiograp'hy  in  the 
Iristory  of  science,  literature,  and 
thought,  a  definition  of  the  exact 
place  and  importance  which  belongs 
to  him  and  his  work.  This  is  what 
is  given  in  such  a  masterly  and  con- 
<deneed  form  in  the  better  iloges  of 


Fontenelle,  of  Cuvier,  of  Arago, 
and  other  secretaries  of  the  French 
Academies.  In  Germany  biographi- 
cal literature  is  less  developed  than 
in  this  country,  and  memoirs  are 
almost  absent — those  of  Varnhagen 
von  Ense  and  of  Perthes,  among 
literary  men,  being  remarkable  and 
rare  exceptions.  Similarly  the  great 
correspondence  carried  on  by  Goethe 
through  nearly  sixty  years  is  a 
unique  monument  of  his  genius 
and  his  influence,  comparable  only 
to  that  of  Voltaire  during  the  last 
century.  R.  Haym  in  his  biographies 
of  Hegel,  \Vm.  von  Humboldt,  and 
Herder,  which  combine  the  bio- 
graphical with  the  historical  and 
critical  elements,  has  done  a  great 
work,  and  these  books  are  invalu- 
able contributions  to  the  history  of 
thought.  Justi's  '  Winckelmann '  is 
of  equal  importance  ;  but  Dilthey's 
'  Schleiermacher '  is  unfortunately 
unfinished. 


280  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

honours  and  championships — in  all  the  noble  and  ignoble 
forms  of  racing,  where  much  energy,  which  might  more 
usefully  have  been  merged  in  co-operative  action,  is 
sacrificed  for  the  sake  of  individual  distinction.  But 
where  the  height  of  genius  forbids  emulation,  where  the 
towering  intellect  has  distanced  all  records,  this  indi- 
vidualism has  produced  single  specimens  of  the  greatest 
work,  examples  of  the  highest  moral  worth.  It  is  not  in 
the  courses  of  scientific  work  alone  that  we  shall  have 
occasion  to  mark  the  peculiarity  of  British,  especially  of 
English,  thought ;  but  it  is  interesting  to  note  how  even 
in  this  sphere,  which  more  than  any  other  seems  to  bear 
an  international  and  cosmopolitan  character,  the  genius 
of  the  nation  strongly  asserts  itself,  baffling  every  effort 
to  control  it  or  to  lead  it  into  more  conventional  chan- 
44.  nels.  The  last  fifty  years  have  done  much  to  destroy 
during  the  the  peculiarly  national  customs,  the  idiosyncrasies  of  the 

last  fifty  r 

years.  different  peoples.  English  institutions  have  been  copied 
in  France,  and  German  customs  introduced  into  England ; 
it  has  recently  been  stated  that  the  older  type  of  scientific 
amateur  which  existed  in  this  country  is  dying  out,  being 
rendered  impossible  by  the  more  complicated  machinery 
of  science,  the  manifold  conditions  on  which  progress  de- 
pends. It  seems  to  me  doubtful  whether  this  view  is 
correct.  Surely  the  advance  of  the  highest  kind  of 
thought  will  always  depend  upon  the  unfettered  devel- 
opment of  the  individual  mind,  regardless  of  established 
habits,  of  existing  forms  of  expression,  or  of  adopted 
systems ;  just  as  the  diffusion  and  wholesale  application  of 
single  discoveries  will  depend  on  a  ready  and  efficient  ma- 
chinery and  organisation ;  whilst  their  influence  on  gen- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN    ENGLAND.          281 

eral  thought  and  literature  will  depend  on  the  cultivation 
of  a  perfect  form,  of  an  expressive  and  elegant  style.  The 
French  alone  in  the  beginning  of  the  century  could  boast 
of  the  last ;  the  Germans  have  most  successfully  developed 
the  second ;  whilst  England,  the  country  of  greatest  indi- 
vidual freedom,  has  been  the  land  most  favourable  to  the 
growth  of  genius  as  well  as  eccentricity,  and  has  thus  pro- 
duced a  disproportionate  number  of  new  ideas  and  depart- 
ures. Nor  is  it  to  be  desired  that  the  reliance  of  genius 
on  itself  should  be  in  any  way  curtailed,  as  it  is  impos- 
sible to  foretell  whence  the  new  light  will  come  which  is 
to  illuminate  future  ages.  This  individualism  of  the 
English  mind  presents  other  accompanying  features,  and 
these  are  of  great  interest  to  the  historian  of  thought. 
They  manifest  themselves  in  the  province  of  science  as 
much  as  in  other  provinces.  We  will  now  study  them 
more  closely ;  in  the  sequel  we  shall  meet  with  them  in 
other  departments  also. 

Hitherto  our  observations  on  English  science  have  nearly 
all  referred  to  only  one  side  of  modern  scientific  work, — 
the  side  on  which  lie  the  experimental,  measuring,  and  cal- 
culating sciences ;  those  sciences  which  abroad  are  termed 
"  exact " ;  in  which  mathematical  notions  and  methods, 
be  it  of  measurement  or  of  calculation,  obtain.  But  these 
sciences  cover  only  one  side  of  reality.  We  noticed  how  in 
France,  during  the  great  scientific  epoch,  the  other  side  of 
nature,  that  which  exhibited  and  was  filled  by  the  pheno- 
mena of  life,  was  simultaneously  explored  with  equal 
originality  and  equal  success.  As  Laplace  was  the  great 
representative  of  the  one,  so  Cuvier  was  the  great  re- 
presentative of  the  other.  We  have  also  seen  how  in 


282 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


45. 

British  con- 


biology. 


Germany  this  latter  department  of  research  was  specially 
cultivated,  how  all  the  mathematical,  experimental,  and 
philosophical  sciences  combined  to  organise  the  one  great 
science  of  physiology  or  biology,  with  its  central  and 
crowning  problem  —  the  problem  of  consciousness.  We 
also  noted  how  this  science  worked  a  great  reform  in 
the  whole  domain  of  medical  theory  and  practice.  Let 
us  now  return  to  the  question,  What  has  Great  Britain 
done  during  the  first  half  of  this  century  in  this  great 
department  of  scientific  thought  ?  Single  great  names,  like 
those  of  Harvey,1  marked  in  former  centuries  discoveries 
in  the  natural  sciences  equal  to  those  of  Newton  in  the 
mathematical;  the  name  of  Ray2  is  still  preserved  in  the 


1  William  Harvey  (1578-1657),  a 
native  of  Kent,  received  his  medical 
education  in  Italy,  especially  in 
Padua,  under  Fabricius  of  Acqua- 
pendente.  The  discovery  of  the 
circulation  of  the  blood  belongs  to 
the  year  1616,  and  is  almost  con- 
temporary with  Napier's  invention 
of  logarithms.  This  discovery  is  con- 
tained in  the  manuscript  of  Harvey's 
lectures  preserved  in  the  British 
Museum,  but  the  publication  did  not 
take  place  till  1628  ('  Exercitatio 
anatomica  de  motu  corporis  et  san- 
guinis  in  animalibus,'  published  at 
Frankfort).  Although  Harvey  was 
drawn  into  long  controversies  by 
his  publication  of  this  work,  he 
had  the  satisfaction  of  seeing  his 
discovery  generally  recognised.  Des- 
cartes abroad  took  Harvey's  part  in 
his  letter  to  Beverwijck  in  1637,  and 
in  his  '  Discours  de  la  Me"thode,'  pub- 
lished in  the  same  year  ;  and  it  is 
noteworthy  that — as  has  been  the 
case  with  many  subsequent  English, 
discoveries — the  first  great  acknow- 
ledgment came  from  the  Continent, 
notably  Holland.  The  acceptance  in 
France  by  the  faculties  of  Paris  and 


Montpellier  was  less  rapid,  and  in 
England  it  is  well  known  that  Lord 
Bacon  took  no  notice  either  of 
Harvey's  discovery  or  of  Napier's 
invention.  See  James  Spedding's 
preface  to  the  "De  interpretatione 
Naturae  Prooemium"  in  works  of 
Lord  Bacon,  vol.  iii.  p.  507,  &c. ;  also 
Harvey'sown  opinion  on  Bacon,  ibid., 
p.  515.  Hobbes,  on  the  other  hand, 
"  was  eager  to  accept  Harvey's  revo- 
lutionary discovery  "  (Groom  Rob- 
ertson, '  Hobbes,'  p.  123),  and  refers 
to  Harvey  in  the  dedication  of  the 
'De  Corpore'  (1655)  as  "the  only 
man  I  know  that,  conquering  envy, 
hath  established  a  new  doctrine  in 
his  lifetime"  (ibid.,  p.  187  n.)  On 
Harvey's  other  works,  notably  on 
the  work '  De  Generatione.'  see,  inter 
alia,  Huxley,  '  Science  and  Culture,' 
1888,  p.  333,  &c. 

2  John  Ray,  or  Rajus,  as  he  is 
called  abroad  (1628-1705),  a  native 
of  Essex,  was  a  Cambridge  man  ; 
he,  however,  gave  up  his  fellowship 
in  1662,  feeling  himself  unable  to 
subscribe  to  the  Act  of  Uniformity 
of  1661.  He  was  one  of  the  first 
great  classifiers  of  plants ;  he  col- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


283 


Society  called  after  him :  in  more  recent  times  Hutton 
formed  a  school  in  geology  which  was  opposed  to  that  of 
Werner,  emanating  from  Germany.1  Hunter,  the  anato- 


lected  a  vast  amount  of  information, 
beginning  with  the  neighbourhood 
of  Cambridge  and  extending  it  in 
travels  over  Great  Britain  and  the 
Continent  with  Willoughby.  The 
'  Historia  Plantarum  ' — describing 
18,625  species  of  plants — appeared 
from  1685  to  1704  in  3  vols.  The 
first  volume  contains  a  chapter  on 
the  anatomy  and  physiology  of 
plants,  which  was  much  extolled 
by  Cuvier  and  recommended  for 
republication.  The  "  Ray  Society," 
started  in  1844  "  for  the  pub- 
lication of  works  on  Natural  His- 
tory," brought  out  among  many 
other  excellent  and  celebrated 
works  (such  as  Darwin's  '  Mono- 
graph of  the  Family  Cirripedia '), 
Memorials  (1844)  and  Correspond- 
ence (1848)  of  John  Ray  :  it  also 
translated  that  eccentric  specimen 
of  the  "  Naturphilosophie  "  Oken's 
'  Elements  of  Physio  -  philosophy,' 
1847.  A  contemporary  of  John  Ray 
was  Nehemiah  Grew  (1628-1711), 
one  of  the  first  to  make  extensive 
use  of  the  microscope  (invented  in 
Holland  between  1590  and  1600) 
for  the  examination  of  the  anatomy 
and  physiology  of  plants.  After 
Oldenburg  he  was  Secretary  of  the 
Royal  Society  together  with  Hooke. 
The  Society  printed  his  '  Anatomy 
of  Plants.'  About  the  same  time 
it  seems  to  have  exhausted  its 
funds  in  printing  Willoughby's 
'  Historia  Piscium,'  so  that  it  was 
unable  to  carry  out  its  design  of 
defraying  the  cost  of  printing  the 
'  Principia. '  This  was  generously 
clone  by  Halley.  See  Weld,  '  His- 
tory of  the  Royal  Society,'  vol.  i. 
p.  309,  &c. 

1  Beneath  the  strife  of  the  Wer- 
nerians  and  Huttonians,  or  the 
Neptunists  and  Plutonists  as  they 


were  termed,  the  real  merits  of 
Robert  Jameson  (1774-1854)  and 
James  Hutton  (1726  -  97)  have 
sometimes  been  overlooked.  Both 
were  ardent  naturalists  who  spent 
their  lives  in  observation  and  study 
of  nature.  They  made  Edinburgh 
for  some  time  the  centre  of  geology 
in  this  country.  Jameson  was  fifty 
years  Professor  of  Natural  History, 
founded  the  first  school  of  Natural 
History  in  this  country  (see  Cossar 
Ewart's  address,  quoted  by  Sir  A. 
Grant,  '  Story  of  the  University  of 
Edinburgh,'  vol.  ii.  p.  444),  trained 
a  number  of  eminent  naturalists, 
amongwhom  are  Edward  Forbes  and 
Grant  (N.B. — The  name  of  Darwin 
must  be  added  with  caution,  see  his 
'  Autobiography,'  vol.  i.  p.  44,  &c.), 
founded  the  Edinburgh  Museum  of 
Natural  History,  which  includes  the 
Huttonian  collections,  and  founded 
the  Wernerian  and  Plinian  Societies 
of  Natural  History.  James  Hutton, 
though  not  a  teacher  like  Jameson, 
exerted  a  great  influence  through 
John  Playfair,  who  popularised  his 
views  in  his  '  Illustrations  of  the 
Huttonian  Theory  of  the  Earth' 
(1802).  It  is  termed  by  Geikie  a 
' '  classical  contribution  to  geological 
literature."  Though  the  opposition 
of  Button's  theoretical  views  to 
those  of  Werner  gave  him  a  great 
reputation  as  a  theorist,  it  is  claimed 
for  him  that  he  first  among  geolo- 
gists disclaimed  the  intention  of 
investigating  the  origin  of  things, 
and  thus  put  an  end  to  the  cosmo- 
gonies of  the  eighteenth  century. 
Such  had  been  promulgated  in  all 
the  three  countries  by  the  most 
illustrious  philosophers  and  natural- 
ists, by  Burnet,  Buffon,  and  Leibniz. 
On  Hutton's  great  merits  see  es- 
pecially Huxley,  "  Essay  on  Geolo- 


284 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


46. 

Jenner. 


mist,  acquired  a  world-wide  reputation  in  the  latter  part 
of  the  eighteenth  century. 

Many  other  students  of  nature  could  be  added  to  this 
list.  Perhaps  none  has  acquired  greater  popular  celebrity 
than  Jenner.1  This  he  acquired  through  his  extraordinary 
discovery,  by  which  he  grappled  successfully  with  one  of 
the  most  prevalent  and  distressing  epidemics  from  which 
47.  former  generations  had  to  suffer.  The  study  of  animated 

English  love 

of  nature,  nature,  the  observation  of  the  sky  and  the  heavens,  have 
always  been  favourite  occupations  of  Englishmen.  The 
love  of  travels  abroad  and  of  the  country  at  home  has 
favoured  a  close  intercourse  with  nature.  A  fickle  and 
humid  climate  invited  the  superior  skill  of  the  agriculturist 
and  the  gardener,  and  rewarded  them  with  heavier  crops 
and  more  luxuriant  verdure.2  The  chill  of  the  long  winter 


gical  Reform"  (1869.  Reprinted 
in  'Lay  Sermons  and  Addresses,' 
No.  11).  He  is  there  considered 
as  the  first  representative  of  "  Uni- 
formitarianism "  against  the  older 
"  Catastrophism."  Uniformitarian- 
ism  has  been  followed  by  "  Evolu- 
tionism. " 

1  Edward  Jenner  (1749-1823), 
one  of  the  greatest  benefactors  of 
mankind,  spent  twenty  years  on 
the  farms  of  Gloucestershire,  fol- 
lowing the  advice  of  his  friend  and 
master  John  Hunter,  "  Don't  think, 
but  try, "  before  he  undertook  the 
first  inoculation  of  cowpox  on  the 
14th  of  May  1796.  About  the  end 
of  the  century  the  process  of  vacci- 
nation, which  dispelled  the  older 
process  of  inoculation — introduced 
into  England  by  Lady  Mary  "W. 
Montagu  in  1721 — had  become 
generally  known  in  Europe.  The 
governments  of  the  Revolution  in 
France  and  the  Academy  of  Sci- 
ences had  at  the  end  of  the  century 
occupied  themselves  a  good  deal 


with  the  cure  of  smallpox,  both  Vol- 
taire and  d'Alembert  having  taken 
great  interest  in  the  subject. 

2  The  yield  of  an  acre  in  wheat 
is  in  England  about  30  bushels  or 
one  ton  of  grain  ;  next  comes  Bel- 
gium, then  Germany,  then  France  ; 
the  average  yield  in  the  United- 
States  of  America  is  barely  one-half 
of  that  in  England.  The  yield  or. 
an  acre  in  Scotland  exceeds  slightly 
that  hi  England.  In  Scotland  farm- 
ing is  carried  on  with  much  skill 
and  enterprise,  and,  in  spite  of  the 
severe  climate,  gardening  is  prob- 
ably further  developed  there  than 
in  any  other  country.  It  appears 
that  the  first  voluntary  organisa- 
tion for  the  improvement  of  agri- 
culture was  the  "  Society  of  Im- 
provers in  the  Knowledge  of  Agri- 
culture in  Scotland "  formed  in 
1723,  of  which  the  Earl  of  Stair 
was  one  of  the  leaders.  Though  it 
counted  300  members,  it  was  short- 
lived :  its  '  Select  Transactions ' 
were  published  by  Maxwell  in  1743. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND.  285 

stimulated  active  exercise  and  outdoor  sport;  the  abun- 
dant rains,  which  fed  the  many  rivulets  with  a  constant 
supply  of  fresh  water,  suggested  the  cultivation  of  that 
pastime  of  which  Izaak  Walton  had  left  a  classical  de- 
scription, long  before  Eousseau  in  France  made  the  love 
of  nature  a  fashionable  sentiment.     Lord  Bacon  pointed 
to  the  study  of  natural  phenomena  as  the  only  source 
of  knowledge.     Evelyn  wrote  a  treatise  on  forest-trees, 
and  the  old-fashioned  English  flower-garden  is  immor- 
talised in  Bacon's  '  Essays,'  in  the  "  Winter's  Tale,"  in 
Cowper's  "  Task,"  and  in  the  works  of  many  other  poets. 
Through  the  literature  of  the  eighteenth  century  there 
runs  a  vein  of  increasing  love  and  knowledge  of  natural 
objects  and  natural  scenery,  beginning  in  Thomson  and 
Gray,  widening  and  deepening  in  Erasmus  Darwin  and 
Cowper,   and    attaining    full   vigour    and   originality   in 
Burns  and  Wordsworth,  as  also  in  the  school  of  English 
landscape-painting.     William  and  Caroline  Herschel  corn- 
Next  caine  the  Bath  and  West  of      kind),  by  which  funds  were  raised, 
England  Society,  1777 ;  the  High-      and  an  eminent  chemist  engaged  " 
land  Society,   1784;    and   the  Na-       ('Ency.    Brit.,'    article    "Agricul- 
tional  Board  of  Agriculture,  1793.       ture,"  vol.  i.  p.  305).     There  is  pro- 
The  'Farmer's  Magazine'  was  start-       bably  no  country  where  farming  is 
ed  in  1800.     About  the  same  time    j  such  a  favourite  pursuit  of  gentle- 
that  Lawes  and  Gilbert  in  England    '   men  of  leisure  and  wealth  as  Great 
and  Liebig  in  Germany  gave  such      Britain,  or  where  the  intelligence 
an    impetus    to    scientific   farming      of  higher  society  and  of  the  univer- 
through  their  experiments  and  pub-    j  sities  is  so  liberally  transferred  to 
lications,  "Mr  John  Finnic  at  Swan-      the  benefit  of  the  country,  of  its 
ston,  near  Edinburgh,  having  sug-    |   population,  its  crops,  and  its  live- 
gested  (1842)  to  some  of  his  neigh-    ;  stock.     Among  many  examples  of 
bours  the  desirableness  of  obtaining   j  the  past  and  present  I  mention  as 
the  aid  of  chemistry  to  guide  far-      an  outcome  of  this  spirit  the  little 
rners  in  many  departments  of  their      volume  by  Sir  Thomas  Dyke  Ac- 
business,    the    hint  was   promptly   i   land,  '  On  the  Chemistry  of  Farm- 
acted  upon,  and  these  Mid-Lothian   i  ing'     (London:    Simpkin    &    Co., 
tenant-farmers   had   the   merit  of      1891),    and    his    liberal    patronage 
originating  an  Agricultural  Chem-    ;   of  agriculture  in  the  west  of  Eng- 
istry  Association   (the   first  of  its      land. 


286  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

menced  the  long  line  of  amateur  star-gazers  of  this 
country ;  Luke  Howard's  study  of  clouds  drew  from  the 
kindred  spirit  which  lived  in  the  great  Goethe  a  loving 
memorial;1  and  John  Dalton  was  induced  by  the  mists 
and  fogs  of  his  native  lake  country  to  join  in  the  foun- 
dation of  the  modern  science  of  meteorology. 
48.  We  now  discover  the  reason  why  the  strong  individual  - 

Union  of  in- 
dividualism  ism  of  the  English  character,  which  prompted  new  de- 

smd  natural- 

E™  toid.  pastures  and  inspired  new  ideas  in  science,  as  it  produced 
adventures  and  novel  enterprise  in  life  and  arts,  has  not 
more  frequently  led  to  discouraging  failures  in  the  latter, 
or  to  eccentricity  and  dreaminess  in  the  former;  why  it 
has,  on  the  whole,  alike  in  practical  work  and  in  scientific 
study,  been  rewarded  by  signal  success.  The  rare  genius, 
gifted  with  the  power  of  original  thought,  who  found  no 
academy  ready  to  call  him,  no  schools  where  he  could  be 
trained,  no  university  eager  to  nurse  and  develop  his 

1  Luke    Howard    (1772-1864),   a  Bestimmt  das  Uubestimmte,  schrankt  es 

member  of  the  Society  of  Friends,  ;    ^"1  es  treffend  !-Sey  die  Ehre  Dein ! 

was  one  of  the  many  lovers  of  nature  ;    \vie  Streife.  steigt,  sich  ballt,  zerflattert, 

and    amateur    naturalists    of    this  fallt, 

country  in  whom  new  sciences— like  |    Krinnre  dankbar  Deiner  sich  die  Welt." 

that  of   meteorology  —  are   nursed  ', 

during  their  unpretentious  infancy.  !    Goethe  subsequently  tried  to  get 

He  himself  gave  a  simple  narrative  :   some  information  about  Howard  s 

of  his  life  and  doings  to  the  great  way  °f  !lfe'      •S°Jt!ia*  I  ™l!>ht  *** 

Goethe,  who,  attracted  by  his  at-  how  such  a  mmd  18  formed-  what 

tempted    classification     of     clouds  :   opportunities,  what  circumstances, 

(about  1802,  published  in  his  <Cli-  have  led  him  unto  ways  of  looking 

mate  of  London'),  had   addressed  »*  \ature  naturally,  have  taught 

some  lines  to  him,    accompanying  him  how  to  devote  himself  to  her,  so 

them  by  a  statement  in  verse  of  M  to  find  her  laws  and  to  prescribe 

Howard's  description  of  the  stratus,  these  agaia  to  her  m  a  natural  hu,man 

cumulus,  cirrus,  and  nimbus  :—  I    manner.'      In  his  autobiographical 

narrative  (reprinted  in  the  last  vol- 

"Er  aber,   Howard,   giebt   mit   reinem  UDQe   of   Goethe's  Works)   Howard 

Sinn  refers  to  the  meteoric  phenomena 

Uns  neuer  Lehre  herrlichsten  Gewinn  :  of    jj^     mentioned   also  in  Cow- 

u££ n  ni     erre   en    Per'8  Letters  <13th  June  1788)' and 

Er  fasst  es  an,  er  halt  zuerst  es  fest ;  White's  '  History  of  Selborne. ' 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


287 


talent,  did  not  retire  into  the  depths  of  his  own  con- 
sciousness, or  surround  himself  with  the  artificial  at- 
mosphere of  erudition.  The  result  of  such  a  process 
can  be  abundantly  traced  in  other  countries  and  other 
literatures.  In  England  the  isolation  from  society  and 
the  solitariness  of  genius  threw  him  into  the  arms  of 
Nature,  and  she  has  in  many  instances,  in  science,  in 
poetry,  and  in  art,  rewarded  and  refreshed  him  by  a 
novel  inspiration — she  has  lifted  her  veil  to  his  loving 
eye  and  revealed  to  him  one  of  her  secrets.  The  in- 
dividualism of  English  science  has  been  tempered  by 
its  naturalism.  A  type  of  this  peculiar  form  of  the 
naturalist  was  Gilbert  White,  the  natural  historian  of 
Selborne.1 


1  A  long  list  might  be  given  of 
these  retired  nature -loving  souls, 
among  whom  Charles  Darwin  will 
always  rank  as  the  greatest  and 
most  conspicuous.  I  give  here  a 
few  names  in  addition  to  those 
mentioned  in  the  text. 

John  Gough  of  Kendal  (1757- 
1825)  might,  according  to  John 
Dalton  (see  his  Life  by  Henry,  pp. 
9  and  10),  "be  deemed  a  prodigy 
in  scientific  attainments.  .  .  .  De- 
prived of  sight  in  infancy  by  the 
smallpox,  .  .  .  possessing  great 
powers  of  mind,  he  bent  them 
chiefly  to  the  study  of  the  physical 
and  mechanical  sciences.  It  was  he 
who  first  set  the  example  of  keeping 
a  meteorological  journal  at  Kendal ; 
...  he  knew  by  the  touch,  taste, 
and  smell  almost  every  plant  within 
twenty  miles ;  he  could  reason  with 
astonishing  perspicuity  on  the  con- 
struction of  the  eye,  the  nature  of 
light  and  colours,  and  of  optic 
glasses,"  &c.,  &c.  For  about  eight 
years  Dalton  and  he  were  intimately 
acquainted. 


George  Edwards  (1694-1773)  of 
Stratford,  Essex,  was  the  author  of 
the  '  History  of  Birds,'  which  he 
published  between  1743  and  1764 
in  six  volumes.  He  had  journeyed 
through  France  and  other  countries, 
and  gave  engravings  of  six  hundred 
subjects  not  before  delineated  by 
naturalists. 

Still  more  remarkable  wasThomas 
Edward  (1814-86),  the  shoemaker 
of  Banff,  who,  having  been  turned 
out  of  three  schools  for  his  zoolo- 
gical propensities,  without  friends, 
without  a  single  book  on  natural 
history,  not  knowing  the  names  of 
the  creatures  he  found,  gained  a 
knowledge  unique  in  its  freshness 
and  accuracy.  At  the  University 
of  Aberdeen,  where  he  exhibited 
his  collections,  he  was  told  by  the 
professors  that  he  came  "several 
centuries  too  soon,"  as  they  had 
then  no  chair  of  Natural  History. 
His  life  has  been  written  by  Smiles, 
1876. 

Edward  Forbes  (1815-54)  of 
Douglas,  Isle  of  Man,  a  born  lover 


288 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


49. 

White  of 
Selborne. 


Not  long  after  Bay  and  Linnaeus  had  attempted  the 
artificial  and  logical  classification  of  living  beings,  and 
about  the  same  time  that  Buffon  in  France  infused  into  the 
literature  of  his  country  a  somewhat  pretentious  love  of 
nature,  Gilbert  White,  in  a  simpler  and  more  healthy  style, 
betook  himself  to  describe  the  aspect  that  nature  presented 
when  viewed  from  the  quiet  home  of  an  English  country 
parson.  He  may  be  said  to  have  represented  that  other 


of  nature,  "led  an  unusually  full 
life,  occupied  in  promoting  science 
and  arousing  enthusiasm  and  awak- 
ening intelligence  in  others.  To 
almost  every  department  of  biology 
he  rendered  much  service,  especially 
by  connecting  various  branches  to- 
gether and  illustrating  one  by  the 
other.  Though  his  published  works 
have  been  few,  his  ideas  have  been 
as  the  grain  of  mustard-seed  in  the 
parable "  ('  Dictionary  of  National 
Biography ').  After  holding  various 
badly  paid  offices  in  London  and 
elsewhere,  he  succeeded  Robert 
Jameson  as  Professor  of  Natural 
History  at  Edinburgh  (see  '  Memoir 
of  E.  Forbes,'  by  G.  Wilson  and  A. 
Geikie,  1861). 

Hugh  Miller  (1802-56),  the  self- 
taught  stonemason  of  Cromarty, 
combined  the  soul  of  an  artist  with 
that  of  a  naturalist.  His  writings 
occupy  a  place  by  themselves  in 
English  Literature.  "The  principal 
scene  of  his  own  investigations  was 
the  Cromarty  district,  where  he 
ransacked  every  wrinkle  of  the  hill- 
side, and  traced  every  stratum  sawn 
through  by  the  watercourse,  and 
where  on  the  beach  at  ebb,  in  in- 
durated clay  of  bluish  tint  and 
great  tenacity,  belonging  to  the  old 
Red  Sandstone  formation,  he  dis- 
covered and  dug  out  nodules  which, 
when  laid  open  by  a  skilful  blow  of 
the  hammer,  displayed  organisms 
that  had  never  been  seen  by  the 
human  eye."  In  September  1840 


there  appeared  in  the  '  Witness '  a 
series  of  articles  entitled  "  The  Old 
Red  Sandstone."  They  formed  the 
nucleus  of  a  book  of  this  title  which 
established  the  reputation  of  Miller 
as  an  original  geologist,  as  a  prac- 
tical thinker  and  fascinating  writer. 
'My  Schools  and  Schoolmasters'  is  a 
masterpiece  of  the  English  language. 
"  In  an  age  prodigal  of  genius,  yet 
abounding  also  in  extravagance, 
glare,  and  bombast,  the  self-edu- 
cated stonemason  wrote  with  the 
calmness  and  moderation  of  Addi- 
son."  "The  fossil  remains  seem 
in  his  glowing  pages  to  live  and 
flourish,  to  fly,  swim,  or  gambol,  or 
to  shoot  up  in  vegetative  profusion 
and  splendour,  as  in  the  primal 
dawn  of  creation "  (Carruthers, 
quoted  by  Peter  Bayne  in  'The 
Life  and  Letters  of  Hugh  Miller,' 
2  vols.,  1871). 

David  Robertson,  the  naturalist 
of  Cumbrae  in  the  Firth  of  Clyde 
(born  in  1806),  was  a  farm-labourer 
till  he  was  twenty  -  four,  then 
took  to  the  study  of  medicine, 
and  had  afterwards  for  many 
years  a  china  and  hardware  shop 
in  Jail  Square,  Glasgow.  He 
gained  a  sufficient  independence  to 
be  able  to  retire  in  1860  to  Great 
Cumbrae,  where  he  devoted  the 
rest  of  his  life  to  a  study  of  nature. 
Especially  in  "  the  marine  section, 
by  his  own  unaided  efforts,  he 
opened  up  in  a  remarkable  degree 
the  zoology  of  the  Firth  of  Clyde. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN    ENGLAND. 


289 


side  of  natural  science,  which  does  not  try  to  comprehend 
nature  through  the  artificial  arrangement  or  classification 
of  a  museum,  but  in  those  connections,  among  her  own 
animate  and  inanimate  objects,  which  constitute  reality, 
and  are  the  characteristics  of  life  and  development.  It 
was  the  real,  not  the  artificial,  Jardiri  des  Plantes, 
where  he  and  his  successors  tried  to  study  natural 
objects  and  the  habits  of  living  beings.1  Another  re- 


Many  animals,  till  then  accounted 
rare,  are  now  known  to  exist  as 
common  objects,  while  the  annals 
of  science  have  received  many  im- 
portant additions  of  animals  alto- 
gether new  to  natural  history 
records  —  discoveries  which  have 
caused  the  Firth  of  Clyde,  and  more 
particularly  the  Cumbrae  Islands, 
to  become  one  of  the  best  explored 
and  most  widely  known  districts 
of  Britain "  (Gray,  Secretary  of 
the  Glasgow  Natural  History  So- 
ciety, quoted  by  Thomas  R.  R. 
Stebbing  in  his  '  Naturalist  of  Cum- 
brae,' London,  1891). 

William  Pearson  (1767-1847)  of 
Borderside,  Crosthwaite,  near  Ken- 
dal,  was  a  self-educated  yeoman, 
who  after  many  years  spent  in  a 
bank  at  Manchester  retired  to  a 
small  patrimonial  estate  on  the 
southern  border  of  Westmorland. 
He  possessed  a  choice  collection  of 
books,  representing  fully  the  English 
poets  of  all  ages,  and  in  translation 
the  best  German  authors.  "  Of 
the  habits  of  birds  and  other  native 
creatures  around  him  he  was  a 
watchful  observer,  and  he  described 
them  in  purest  English  with  a 
charm  that  suggested  no  disadvan- 
tageous comparison  with  White  of 
Selborne "  (see  Groves,  '  Life  of 
Hamilton,'  vol.  iii.  p.  15).  He  was 
a  friend  of  Wordsworth. 

To  this  list,  which  could  be  in- 
definitely extended,  I  might  add 
another,  beginning  with  Thomas 

VOL.  I. 


Bewick  (1753-1828),  the  reviver  of 
wood  -  engraving  in  England,  who 
lent  his  art  and  life  to  the  delinea- 
tion of  nature.  '  British  Birds ' 
(1797-1804)  is  a  standard  work  on 
the  borderland  of  art  and  science, 
in  which  many  other  British  artists 
have,  in  humbler  or  more  extensive 
fields,  laboured  with  so  much  faith- 
fulness and  success. 

1  The  '  Complete  Angler '  and  the 
'Natural  History  of  Selborne,'  are 
types  of  a  class  of  literature  peculiar 
to  this  country.  In  these  classical 
productions  we  are  introduced  into 
the  nursery  of  English  thought,  po- 
etry— nay,  of  science  itself.  These, 
as  the  nation  draws  ultimately  its 
wealth  from  the  produce  and  culture 
of  the  land,  on  their  part  receive 
valuable  ideas  from  a  study  of 
nature.  The  purity  and  origin- 
ality of  English  art  and  poetry  have 
their  home  in  the  same  region. 
Gilbert  White  (1720-93)  was  born 
and  lived  in  the  little  Hampshire 
village  of  Selborne.  He  was  one  of 
five  brothers,  all  of  whom,  in  vari- 
ous positions  and  vocations  of  life, 
followed  the  study  of  nature  in  its 
minute  and  local  aspects,  combining 
with  it  an  antiquarian  taste.  He 
may  not  only  be  classed  with  the 
naturalists,  but  belongs  also  to  that 
class  of  writers,  peculiar  also  to  Eng- 
land, who  devote  their  time  to  the 
compilation  of  local  records,  of 
county  histories,  and  to  the  preser- 
vation of  the  relics  and  memorials 


290 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


action  against  the  theorising  methods  which  had  come 
over  from  the  Continent  led  to  the  formation  of  the 
Geological  Society  in  the  year  1807.  At  that  time 
the  war  of  the  Wernerians  and  Huttonians,  or,  as  they 
were  also  called,  the  Xeptunists  and  Plutonists,  was  rag- 
so,  ing  in  the  northern  metropolis.  The  Geological  Society 

The  Geologi- 
cal society.   of  London  was  established  with  a  view  to  "  multiply  and 

record  observations,  and  patiently  to  await  the  result  at 
some  future  period — that  is,  its  founders  resolved  to  apply 
themselves  to  descriptive  geology,  thinking  the  time  not 
come  for  that  theoretical  geology  which  had  then  long 
fired  the  controversial  ardour  of  Xeptunists  and  Plu- 
tonists." ]  Fifty  years  after  the  formation  of  this  society 


of  country  life  in  bygone  centuries. 
The  series  of  letters  written  be- 
tween the  years  1765  and  1787 
containing  "the  observations  of 
forty  years,"  and  published,  1789, 
with  the  title  '  The  Natural  History 
and  Antiquities  of  Selborne,'  had 
the  object  "of  laying  before  the 
public  his  idea  of  parochial  history, 
which,  he  thinks,  ought  to  consist 
of  natural  productions  and  occur- 
rences as  well  as  antiquities."  To 
him  "nature  is  so  full  that  that  dis- 
trict produces  the  greatest  variety 
which  is  the  most  examined."  He 
early  insiste  on  the  necessity  of 
monographs  in  natural  history ; 
suggests  the  usefulness  of  a  "  full 
history  of  noxious  insects";  gives 
in  a  series  of  letters  a  faithful  and 
minute  description  of  the  swallow 
tribe  as  they  are  found  in  his 
country  ;  traverses  the  Downs  of 
Surrey  with  a  loving  eye  a  hundred 
years  before  they  became  celebrated 
through  the  greater  Darwin  ;  makes 
valuable  observations  about  '"earth- 
worms," suggesting  a  monograph 
on  them  ;  suggests,  in  an  age  which 
was  governed  by  the  systematising 


mania,  that  "the  botanist  should 
study  plants  philosophically,  should 
investigate  the  laws  of  vegetation, 
should  promote  their  cultivation, 
and  graft  the  gardener,  the  planter, 
and  the  husbandman  on  the  phy- 
tologist,"  as  "system  should  be 
subservient  to,  not  the  main  object 
of,  pursuit." 

1  "The  one  point  the  catastro- 
phists  and  the  uniformitarians 
agreed  upon  when  this  society  was 
founded  was  to  ignore  it  [vi:.,  geo- 
logical speculation].  And  you  will 
find,  if  you  look  back  into  our  re- 
cords, that  our  revered  fathers  in 
geology  plumed  themselves  a  good 
deal  upon  the  practical  sense  and 
wisdom  of  this  proceeding.  As  a 
temporary  measure  I  do  not  pre- 
sume to  challenge  its  wisdom  ;  but 
in  all  organised  bodies  temporary 
changes  are  apt  to  produce  per- 
manent effects ;  and  as  time  has 
slipped  by,  altering  all  the  condi- 
tions which  may  have  made  such 
mortification  of  the  scientific  flesh 
desirable,  I  think  the  effect  of  the 
stream  of  cold  water  which  has 
steadily  flowed  over  geological  specu- 


THE    SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   ENGLAND. 


291 


the  author  from  whom  I  quote,  Dr  Whewell,  in  the  third 
edition  of  his  '  History  of  the  Inductive  Sciences/  could 
still  say  that  "  their  task  was  not  yet  finished,  their  mis- 
sion not  yet  accomplished — that  they  had  still  much  to 
do  in  the  way  of  collecting  facts ;  and  in  entering  upon 
the  exact  estimation  of  causes,  they  have  only  just  thrown 
open  the  door  of  a  vast  labyrinth  which  it  may  employ 
many  generations  to  traverse,  but  which  they  must  needs 
explore  before  they  can  penetrate  to  the  Oracular  Chamber 
of  Truth."  l  One  of  the  many  individuals  in  this  country  51. 

J    William 

who  "  had  long  pursued  his  own  thoughts  without  aid  and  smith, 
without  sympathy  "  2  was  William  Smith.     "  No  literary 


lation  within  these  walls  has  been 
of  doubtful  beneficence "  (Huxley 
on  "Geological  Reform,"  Address 
to  the  Geological  Society,  1869  ; 
reprinted  in  'Lay  Sermons,'  &c., 
1891,  p.  207). 

1  See  Whewell,  '  History  of  the 
Inductive  Sciences,'  3rd  ed.,  vol.  iii. 
pp.  428,  518.     Lyell,  'Principles  of 
Geology,'  3rd  ed.,  vol.  i.  p.  102,  &c. 

2  Whewell,  loc.   cit.,   vol.    iii.    p. 
427.     William   Smith  (1769-1839), 
a  native  of  Oxfordshire,  has  been 
called  the  Father  of  English  Geo- 
logy.    He  was — like  so  many  other 
naturalists    of    this    country  —  an 
amateur  in  his   scientific   studies, 
which  were  conducted  on  the  occa- 
sions  of   his   elaborate  surveys   of 
Oxfordshire,     Warwickshire,     and 
Somersetshire  in   connection   with 
the  engineering  of   several  canals. 
He  initiated  in  England  the  science 
called   on   the   Continent   "  Strati- 
graphy,"   observed    the    successive 
layers  in  the   geological   structure 
of  the  country,  and  in  1799  pre- 
pared a  tabular  view  of  the  order 
of   the    strata    and    their    organic 
remains  in  the   neighbourhood   of 
Bath.     For  many  years  after  this 


he  was  occupied  in  preparing  his 
Geological  Map  of  England  and 
Wales,  which  appeared  on  the  five 
miles  to  the  inch  scale  in  1815  in 
fifteen  sheets.  He  was  popularly 
known  as  "  Stratum  Smith,"  but 
remained  almost  unknown  abroad, 
as  he  himself  also  seems  to  have 
taken  little  notice  of  Continental 
geology  or  prevailing  theories. 
Though  he  began  earlier  than  Cu- 
vier  and  Brongniart,  they  antici- 
pated him  by  publishing  in  1811 
their  mineral  ogical  description  of 
the  Paris  Basin,  thus  becoming  the 
founders  of  the  science  of  palaeon- 
tology (see  Peschel,  'Geschichte 
der  Erdkunde,'  Miinchen,  1877,  p. 
714,  &c.)  Of  the  Geological  Map 
Lyell  says  ('Principles  of  Geology,' 
vol.  i.  p.  101)  that  it  "remains  a 
lasting  monument  of  original  talent 
and  extraordinary  perseverance ;  for 
he  had  explored  the  whole  country 
on  foot  without  the  guidance  of 
previous  observers  or  the  aid  of 
fellow-labourers,  and  had  succeeded 
in  throwing  into  natural  divisions 
the  whole  complicated  series  of 
British  rocks." 


292  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

cultivation  of  his  youth  awoke  in  him  the  speculative 
love  of  symmetry  and  system ;  but  a  singular  clearness 
and  precision  of  the  classifying  power,  which  he  possessed 
as  a  native  talent,  was  exercised  and  developed  by  exactly 
those  geological  facts  among  which  his  philosophical  task 
lay.  Some  of  the  advances  which  he  made  had  been 
entered  upon  by  others  who  preceded  him:  but  of  all 
this  he  was  ignorant,  and  perhaps  went  on  more  steadily 
and  eagerly  to  work  out  his  own  ideas  from  the  persuasion 
that  they  were  entirely  his  own."  In  what  he  did  and 
published,  beginning  with  the  year  1790,  "we  see  great 
vividness  of  thought  and  activity  of  mind  unfolding  itself 
exactly  in  proportion  to  the  facts  with  which  it  had  to 
deal."1 

About  the  same  time  that  geological  studies  received  a 
great  impetus  in  this  country  from  two  distinct  centres — 
the  philosophical  teaching  in  the  Scotch  metropolis,  and 
the  more  empirical  labours  of  the  Geological  Society — a 
signal  discovery  in  another  line  marked  a  great  step  in 
52.  anatomy  and  physiology.  This  was  Charles  Bell's  dis- 

CharlesBelL 

covery,  in  the  year  1807,  of  the  difference  between  sensory 
and  motor  nerves,  "doubtless  the  most  important  accession 
to  physiological  knowledge  since  the  time  of  Harvey." 2 

1  Whewell,  loc.  cit. ,  p.  423.  the  circulation   of   the  blood,  and 

2  This  statement,  taken  from  Dr  opened  up  that  road   to  the   me- 
Henry's  '  Report  of  the  British  As-  chanical  theory  of  these  processes 
sociation,'  vol.  vi.,  and  repeated  by  which  has  been  followed  by  all  his 
Whewell  (loc.  cit.,  vol.  iii.  p.  352),  successors"  (Huxley  in  Ibis  address 
probably  requires  a  correction,  since  to  the  British  Association  at  Bel- 
Du  Bois-Reymond  and  others  have  fast,  1874;    reprinted  in   'Science 
placed  in  their  true  historical  posi-  and  Culture,  &c.,'  p.  200,  &c.)     The 
tion  the  great  merits  of  Descartes,  first  enunciation  of  the  principle  of 
who  by  the  discovery  of  the  principle  reflex   action    had    been    variously 
of   "reflex   action"    "did   for  the  ascribed  to  Joh.  Miiller,  Prochaska, 
physiology  of  motion  and  sensation  Willis,  till  Du  Bois-Reyrnond  in  his 
that  which   Harvey  had  done  for  most  interesting  '  Gediichtnissrede 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND. 


293 


Bell's  career  was  a  unique  one.  He  had  early  severed 
his  connection  with  the  great  medical  schools  of  Edin- 
burgh, where  his  brother  taught.  He  lectured  and  prac- 
tised privately  in  London,  where  he  gained  a  considerable 
reputation ;  but  in  his  case  also  it  was  on  the  Continent 
that  his  greatness  was  more  generally  recognised.  As  in 
Dalton's  case,  his  countrymen  were  slow  to  do  him  justice.1 
In  France  he  had  so  great  a  name  that  a  celebrated 


auf  Job.  Miiller '  (Berlin  Acad. , 
1859)  showed  how  the  merit  of 
enunciating  it  is  due  to  Descartes, 
whose  tract  on  '  Les  Passions  de 
1'Ame '  was  published  in  1649. 
Both  Du  Bois-Reymond  and  Huxley 
give  full  extracts  from  the  writings 
of  Descartes.  There  seems,  however, 
to  be  some  doubt  to  what  extent 
Descartes  substantiated  his  mechan- 
ical view  of  the  action  of  the  nerv- 
ous system  by  actual  experiments. 
Richet  in  his  '  Physiologic  des 
Muscles  et  des  Nerfs'  (Paris,  1882, 
p.  505,  &c.)  refers  to  this,  and 
while  giving  Descartes  his  due, 
also  says  that  practically  from  the 
time  of  Galen  to  Charles  Bell  no 
marked  progress  had  been  made 
in  the  knowledge  of  the  nervous 
system,  and  that  this  belongs  al- 
most entirely  to  the  nineteenth 
century  (pp.  502,  507,  514).  Huxley, 
who  takes  a  much  higher  view  of 
the  merits  of  Descartes,  says  he 
was  not  only  a  speculator,  but  also 
an  observer  and  dissector  (loc.  cit., 
p.  201),  and  actually  places  him 
at  the  head  of  modern  physiology 
(p.  334,  &c.) 

1  Charles  Bell  (1774-1842)  was 
born  at  Edinburgh.  His  elder 
brother,  John  Bell  (1763-1820), 
who  was  a  lecturer  of  great  repute 
in  the  extra-mural  School  of  Surgery 
at  Edinburgh,  first  drew  his  atten- 
tion to  the  medical  profession.  It 
was  only  late  in  life,  and  after  he 


had  gained  his  European  renown, 
that  he  was  appointed  to  the  Chair 
of  Surgery  at  the  University  of 
Edinburgh,  which  had  been  created 
in  1831,  and  it  does  not  appear 
that  he  was  at  all  sufficiently  ap- 
preciated in  this  position  :  he  used 
to  say,  "  I  seem  to  walk  in  a  city  of 
tombs,"  being  unknown  in  the  city 
of  his  birth  (see  Sir  A.  Grant, 
'  University  of  Edinburgh,'  vol.  ii. 
p.  453).  Whilst  Charles  Bell  es- 
tablished the  difference  of  sensory 
and  motor  nerves,  and  dispelled 
"the  confusion  which  prevailed  up 
to  that  time  in  the  minds  of  anato- 
mists and  physiologists  regarding 
the  functions  of  the  various  nerves," 
the  merit  of  proving  by  strict  ex- 
periment the  correctness  of  Bell's 
theorem  belongs  to  Johannes  Miiller 
(1831),  who  showed  it  in  the  frog, 
and  to  Magendie  and  Longet,  who 
succeeded  in  exhibiting  it  in  warm- 
blooded animals.  Up  to  the  date 
of  Miiller's  experimental  proof  no- 
body regarded  "Bell's  doctrine  aa 
more  than  an  ingenious  and  indeed 
plausible,  but  nevertheless  not  suf- 
ficiently demonstrated,  idea"  (see 
Du  Bois-Reymond,  '  Reden,'  vol.  ii. 
p.  176,  &c.  ;  also  Henle's  descrip- 
tion of  the  demonstration  given  by 
Miiller  in  Paris  on  the  13th  Sep- 
tember 1831  to  Humboldt,  Dutro- 
chet,  Valenciennes,  and  Laurillart, 
in  'Jacob  Henle,'  by  Merkel,  1891, 
p.  83). 


294  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

anatomical  professor,  when  Bell  visited  his  lecture-room, 
dismissed  his  class  with  the  words,  "  C'est  assez,  messieurs, 
vous  avez  vu  Charles  Bell." 

In  Germany  one  of  the  great  achievements  of  Johannes 
Mliller,  through  which  he  acquired  European  celebrity, 
was  his  actual  experimental  proof  of  Bell's  thesis,  with 
which  he  had  occupied  himself  for  many  years. 

Instances  might  be  indefinitely  multiplied,  showing  the 
individual  greatness,  but  also  the  isolation,  of  English 
men  of  science  and  their  discoveries  ;  how  the  latter  ema- 
nated so  frequently  from  the  depths  of  original  genius 
in  intimate  communion  with  nature ;  how  they  as  fre- 
quently lacked  those  social  advantages,  that  organisation 
for  development,  which  the  great  schools  and  establish- 
ments of  the  Continent  all  through  the  century  have  pos- 
sessed in  so  eminent  a  degree.  Not  only  in  the  study 
of  nature  has  this  individual  character  of  British  research 
53.  shown  itself,  though  it  is  here  most  conspicuous.  Ln  the 
geography,  exploration  of  foreign  lands  and  the  monuments  of  by- 
gone civilisations — in  the  historical  branches  of  research, 
we  meet  with  similar  pioneer  work.  Who  does  not  recall 
the  names  of  Dr  Young  and  of  Layard  ?  I  will  mention 
only  one  instance  of  this  kind,  where  individual  ability 
joined  to  fortuitous  circumstances  laid  the  foundation  of 
a  new  branch  of  research  on  the  borderland  of  natural 
and  political  history,  the  geography  of  ancient  and  modern 
Greece — the  exploration  of  the  land  which  produced  the 
most  remarkable,  and  perhaps  the  most  intense,  culture 
which  the  world  has  yet  seen.  Note  what  Ernst  Curtius l 

1  See  his  essay  in  the  'Preussische  I  Wetteifer  der  Nationen  in  der 
Jahrbiicher,'  vol.  38,  on  M.  W.  Wiederentdeckung  der  Liinder  des 
Leake,  and  his  discourse,  "Der  i  Alterthuins"  (1880),  both  reprint- 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIRIT    IN   ENGLAND. 


295 


says, — the  man  to  whom  we  are  most  indebted  for  the 
systematic  historical  and  artistic  study  of  this  remarkable 
country ;  whose  mind  has  better  than  any  other  succeeded 
in  representing  to  itself  the  natural  and  ideal  features  of 
that  country  and  that  bygone  race,  and  who  has  drawn  in 
his  writings  a  series  of  pictures,  reproducing  that  past 
glory  in  unequalled  perfection.  In  tracing  the  begin- 
nings of  the  modern  science  of  archaeology  or  historical 
geography,  he  assigns  to  England  and  Englishmen  a  fore- 
most place  as  pioneers.  "  In  England  there  was  no  medi- 
aeval tradition  which  suggested  expeditions  to  the  East, 
nor  did  there  exist  any  external  occasion  or  public  inter- 
est, but  it  was  a  free  and  purely  human  attraction  which 
led  Britons  to  the  classical  soil,  and  private  means  have 
made  all  the  sacrifices  that  were  required  in  order  to 
satisfy  a  craving  of  the  soul.1  .  .  .  England  became  the 


ed  in  that  valuable  collection,  '  Al- 
terthum  und  Gegenwart,'  3  vols., 
Berlin,  1882  and  1889.  In  the  re- 
discovery of  the  countries  of  ancient 
civilisation,  Italians  made  the  be- 
ginning with  Cyriacus  of  Ancona 
(from  1412  to  1442).  Then  follow 
the  French — Jacob  Spon  of  Lyons, 
a  German  by  birth,  being  among 
the  earliest  (1675).  The  generation 
that  succeeded  the  age  of  Scaliger 
produced  the  first  maps  of  Greece 
(Paulmier).  Then  follows  England, 
where  the  name  of  Arundel  has  ac- 
quired a  doubtful  celebrity  through 
that  wholesale  acquisition  of  an- 
cient relics  which  Mr  (afterwards 
Sir  William)  Petty  and  John  Evelyn 
carried  on  in  his  name  in  Greece 
and  Asia  Minor.  It  is  interesting 
to  note  here  the  position  that  Ger- 
many holds  in  the  growing  science 
of  archaeology,  of  which  Winckel- 
rnann  may  be  considered  the  foun- 
der. "The  Germans  possessed  no 


advantages  and  resources  by  which 
they  could  take  part  in  the  con- 
test of  nations  over  the  rediscovery 
of  the  countries  of  ancient  history. 
.  .  .  Whilst  in  Italy  it  was  national 
feeling,  in  France  political  relations 
with  the  East,  in  England  the  love 
of  collecting  and  travelling  common 
among  the  aristocracy,  which  estab- 
lished the  connection  of  the  Old 
World  with  the  New,  in  Germany 
it  was  the  workroom  of  the  profes- 
sor" (Curtius, loc.  cit.,vo\. ii.  p. 229). 
1  E.  Curtius,  foe.  cit.,  vol.  ii.  p.  226. 
"In  the  year  1742  Stuart  and 
Revett  wandered  among  the  ruins 
of  Rome,  and  recognised  that  in 
its  relics  they  beheld  only  later  and 
degenerate  forms  of  ancient  art. 
Six  years  later  they  set  sail  for 
Greece.  It  was,  after  Cyriacus  of 
Ancona  and  Jacob  Spon  of  Lyons, 
the  third  journey  of  exploration  ; 
but  it  was  the  first  in  scientific  im- 
portance" (p.  227). 


296  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

treasury  of  the  wonders  of  the  East,  and  whilst  the  Con- 
tinent was  closed  to  her,  her  travellers  flocked  to  Hellas, 
registering  with  marvellous  patience,  watch  in  hand,  on 
the  back  of  the  slowly  marching  mule,  piece  by  piece,  the 
remains  of  antiquity.  .  .  .  The  political  mission,  headed 
54.  by  Martin  "William  Leake,  was  as  such  quite  unsuccessful : 

Martin 

wiliiam       for  science,  it  was  of  priceless  value :  from  the  moment 

Leake. 

that  Leake  trod  on  classic  soil  the  reminiscences  of  Homel- 
and Herodotus  were  kindled,  and  he  saw  clearly  his  life- 
work  before  him.  Under  the  powerful  impressions  pro- 
duced by  the  great  table-land  of  Asia  Minor  with  the 
solitary  snow-peak  Argaios,  deeply  moved  by  the  deserted 
places,  marching  over  Grecian  inscriptions,  over  sarcophagi 
and  temple  ruins,  he  felt  the  irresistible  charm  of  the 
attempt  to  explore  and  to  understand  these  homes  of 
ancient  culture.1  .  .  .  The  scientific  result  was  a  lasting 
gain  for  the  civilised  world,  and  the  travels  which  he 
made  from  1805  to  1807  mark  an  epoch  in  our  know- 
ledge of  Grecian  antiquity." 2 

But  the  labours  of  the  pioneer  in  science,  life,  or  art, 
which  form  so  conspicuous  an  element  of  this  country's 
mental  work  during  the  first  two-thirds  of  the  century, 
must  be  supplemented  and  carried  further  by  a  great 
army  of  patient  and  trained  explorers.  Original  ideas 
must  be  cast  into  an  appropriate  and  elegant  form  :  new 
discoveries  must  be  extended  and  criticised  by  strict 
methods  of  research ;  erudition  and  philosophy  are  re- 
quired to  guarantee  completeness  and  depth.  In  the 
large  domain  of  the  historical  sciences  these  labours  of 

1  E.  Curtius,  loc.  cit. ,  p.  307. 
3  Ibid.,  p.  312. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND.          297 

the  school  and  the  study  are  even  more  important  than 
in  the  exploration  of  nature,  and  thus  it  is  not  surpris- 
ing that  in  these  especially  the  bulk  of  the  work, 
though  frequently  begun  by  Englishmen,  has  been  car- 
ried on  by  the  great  schools  and  academies  of  the  Con- 
tinent. In  the  regions  of  exact  science,  with  which  we 
are  at  present  more  immediately  concerned,  there  will 
always  be  a  much  greater  inducement  for  original  minds 
to  forsake  the  beaten  track,  the  recognised  method  or 
system. 

The  genius  gifted  with  a  larger  field  of  vision  and  a 
keener  glance  will  always  feel  the  longing  to  return  to 
Nature  herself,  and  the  practical  man  will  be  allured  by 
the  prospects  of  application  of  science  in  the  arts  and 
industries.  Both  will  find  their  reward ;  nor  is  it  likely 
that  the  works  of  Faraday  and  Darwin  should  be  the  last 
illustrious  examples  of  great  and  far-reaching  ideas  sprung 
from  the  living  intercourse  of  original  genius  and  nature 
without  the  support  of  any  school ;  or  that  the  practical 
success  of  the  Atlantic  cable  will  be  the  last  fruit  of 
the  rare  combination  of  highest  mathematical  genius  with 
industrial  and  commercial  enterprise.  The  historian  of 
thought  is  forced  to  admit  that  such  rare  combinations 
are  most  likely  to  spring  up  amongst  a  people  who  have 
always  opposed  the  rule  of  systems  and  methods,  of  schools 
and  academies ;  who  have  nursed  and  cherished  an  inti- 
mate communion  with  nature ;  and  for  whom  practical 
interests  and  adventures  have  always  preserved  an  irre- 
sistible attraction. 

Living  in  an  age  when  the  foundation  in  England  and 
in  Germany  of  institutions  similar  to  the  Academic  Fran- 


298 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


55. 

Work  of 
the  three 
nations 
compared. 


Qaise  has  been  seriously  discussed,1  when  the  British 
Association  has  been  copied  abroad,2  and  when  scientific 
men  of  eminence  are  joined  in  conference  as  to  the  advis- 
ability of  founding  a  professorial  university  in  London, 
in  imitation  of  the  great  University  of  Berlin,  it  seems 
appropriate  to  recall  the  various  ways  and  means  by 
which,  mainly  in  this  century,  the  exact  spirit  of  re- 
search, the  mathematical  method  of  investigating  nature 
and  reality,  has  been  established  and  diffused. 

France  was  the  country  in  which  the  modern  scientific 
methods  of  measurement,  calculation,  and  classification 
were  first  practised  on  a  large  scale,  reduced  to  a  system, 
and  employed  for  the  investigation  of  the  whole  of  nature. 
The  Academy  of  Sciences,  together  with  the  High  Schools 
of  Science,  the  Natural  History  collections,  and  Medical 
Institutions,  all  in  close  connection,  furnished  an  organi- 
sation of  the  highest  intelligences  of  the  nation,  by  which 


1  See  Matthew  Arnold's  essay  on 
'  The   Literary  Influence  of  Acad- 
emies,'   and    Du    Bois  -  Reymond, 
'  Uebereine    Kaiserliche    Akademie 
der  deutschen  Sprache,'  1874,  re- 
printed  in    'Reden,  &c.,'   Leipzig, 
1886,  vol.  i.  p.  141,  &c.    On  the  other 
side  see  Huxley  in  '  Critiques  and 
Addresses,'  ed.  of  1890,  p.  113,  &c. 

2  The   British  Association,  itself 
established  somewhat  on  the  model 
of    the    German    "  Naturforscher- 
Versammlung,"   founded  by  Oken 
and  Humboldt  (see  supra,  p.  238) 
in  the  year  1831,  has  become  the 
model  of    the  younger    "Associa- 
tion  francaise    pour  1'Avancement 
des    Sciences,"    founded    in    1872 
under    the    presidency   of    Claude 
Bernard.     It  held  its  first   public 
meeting  at  Bordeaux  in  1874.      In 
the  opening  addresses  of  the  presi- 
dent, M.   de  Quatrefages,  and  the 


secretary,  M.  Cornu,  the  elder  sis- 
ter in  England  is  referred  to.  A 
characteristic  passage  in  M.  Quatre- 
fages' address  as  regards  the  results 
achieved  by  the  British  Association 
is  the  following :  "  Grace  &  elle 
une  partie  de  la  population  a  e"te 
transformee.  Les  fils  de  ces  chas- 
seurs de  renards,  qui,  pour  se 
de"lasser  de  leurs  rudes  passetemps, 
ne  connaissaient  que  des  joies 
e"galement  violentes  et  materielles, 
sont  aujourd'hui  des  botanistes, 
des  ge"ologues,  des  physiciens,  des 
archeologues  "  ('Comptes  Rendus,' 
lere  session,  p.  40).  Following 
the  resolutions  carried  in  1885, 
the  French  Association  amalga- 
mated in  1886  with  the  older  "  As- 
sociation scientifique  de  France," 
founded  by  Leverrier  in  1864.  See 
'  Compte  Rendu  de  la  16rne  Ses- 
sion,' vol.  i.  p.  1,  &c. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC    SPIEIT   IN   ENGLAND.  299 

a  systematic  exploration  of  the  heavens  and  the  earth, 
the  inanimate  and  the  living  world,  could  be  undertaken. 
At  the  same  time,  the  methods  of  measurement  and  cal- 
culation were  submitted  to  closer  study;  new  sciences 
were  created  by  the  application  of  these  methods ;  and 
problems  were  attacked  for  the  first  time,  with  which, 
at  the  end  of  the  century,  the  scientific  world  is  still 
occupied.  It  was  in  France  also  that  the  discoveries  of 
the  laboratory  were  first  applied  so  as  to  contribute  to 
the  revolution  of  arts  and  industries.  In  all  its  different 
expressions — in  the  production  of  works  of  classical  per- 
fection in  substance  and  in  form,  in  its  application  to  the 
problems  of  life  and  society,  and  in  its  influence  on  gen- 
eral literature — we  find  the  scientific  spirit,  as  we  know 
it,  fully  established  in  France  in  the  beginning  of  the 
century.  About  three  decades  later  we  find  this  spirit 
domiciled  in  Germany,  the  study  of  the  exact  sciences 
having  been  gradually  accepted  at  the  German  univer- 
sities as  an  integral  part  of  the  university  cycle.  It  there 
met  the  philosophical  and  classical  spirit,  which  had  or- 
ganised the  German  university  system  and  the  teaching 
of  the  higher  schools,  and  had  revolutionised  historical, 
especially  philological,  studies.  What  might  have  been 
wanting  at  times  in  French  science,  historical  complete- 
ness and  philosophical  criticism,  was  added  in  Germany. 
Germany  has  in  the  course  of  this  century  not  only  be- 
come the  country  where  the  most  faithful  and  exhaustive 
record  is  kept  of  the  scientific  labours  of  the  whole  world, 
but  it  has  also  become  the  country  where  mainly  those 
problems  have  been  attacked  which  lie  on  the  border- 
land of  natural  science  and  philosophy,  the  problems  of 


300  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

life  and  consciousness.  Modern  physiology,  especially 
psychophysics,  is  claimed  as  essentially  a  German  science. 
Meanwhile  England,  where  the  introduction  of  the 
scientific  spirit  as  an  established  canon  of  systematic  and 
methodical  research  was  later  than  in  other  countries, 
has  all  through  this  century,  as  before,  continued  to 
do  pioneer  work  in  many  isolated  branches  of  science : 
individual,  as  opposed  to  corporate  effort,  has  here  been 
rewarded  by  a  succession  of  brilliant  discoveries,  which 
have  revolutionised  practical  life  or  opened  out  new 
views  into  the  hidden  recesses  of  nature.  For  the 
want  of  organisations  of  research  and  teaching,  such  as 
other  countries  possessed,  these  ideas  of  English  thinkers 
have  frequently  lain  dormant  or  been  elaborated  by 
foreign  talent ;  but  this  want  of  a  recognised  system,  and 
of  a  standard  course  of  study,  has  forced  original  minds 
into  a  closer  communion  with  nature  and  with  life, 
whence  they  have  frequently  returned  to  the  laboratory 
with  quite  novel  revelations.  The  largest  number  of 
works  perfect  in  form  and  substance,  classical  for  all 
time,  belongs  probably  to  France ;  the  greatest  bulk  of 
scientific  work  probably  to  Germany;  but  of  the  new 
ideas  which  during  this  century  have  fructified  science, 
the  larger  share  belongs  probably  to  England.  Such 
seems  to  be  the  impartial  verdict  of  history.  During  the 
second  half  of  the  century  a  process  of  equalisation  has  gone 
on  which  has  taken  away  something  of  the .  characteristic 
peculiarities  of  earlier  times.  The  great  problems  of  science 
and  life  are  now  everywhere  attacked  by  similar  methods. 
Scientific  teaching  proceeds  on  similar  lines,  and  ideas  and 
discoveries  are  cosmopolitan  property.  So  much  more 


THE   SCIENTIFIC   SPIRIT   IN   ENGLAND.          301 

interesting  must  it  be  for  those  who  have  been  born 
members  of  this  international  republic  of  learning  to 
trace  the  way  in  which  this  confederation  has  grown  up 
what  have  been  the  different  national  contributions  to 
its  formation,  and  how  the  spirit  of  exact  science,  once 
domiciled  only  in  Paris,  has  gradually  spread  into  all 
countries,  and  leavened  the  thought  and  literature  of  the 
world. 


302 


CHAPTER   IV. 

THE   ASTRONOMICAL  VIEW   OF  NATURE. 

i.        So  far  I  have  only  treated  of  the  scientific  spirit,  or  of 

The  scien- 
tific spirit     the  method  of  exact  research,  in  a  general  wav ;  showing 

in  the  first  *  ' 

haff ofthe1  now  ^  was  firmly  established  and  developed  in  France, 
'ury-  how  it  spread  into  Germany,  and  received  there  larger 
and  more  systematic  application,  and  how  in  this  country 
it  gradually  and  almost  imperceptibly  grew  out  of  the 
older  experimental  philosophy.  This  growth,  as  we  have 
seen,  took  place  partly  under  the  influence  of  foreign 
science,  but  still  more  through  the  individual  and  un- 
aided labours  of  a  small  number  of  native  intellects  of 
the  very  highest  order,  to  each  of  whom  was  for  a  time 
allotted  the  enunciation  of  some  specially  fruitful  idea, 
The  period  referred  to  in  this  survey  was  mainly  the  first 
half  of  our  century ;  in  it  were  most  clearly  marked  the 
characteristic  differences  between  the  three  great  civilisa- 
tions of  France,  Germany,  and  England.  A  step  further 
in  time  would  lead  into  the  midst  of  our  own  period — 
into  the  age  which  has  largely  reaped  the  benefits  of  those 
earlier  labours,  both  in  theory  and  in  practice,  fully  realis- 
ing in  many  directions  the  predictions  and  even  the  ideals 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        303 

of  the  pioneers  of  science.  One  of  these  benefits,  and 
perhaps  that  which  to  an  external  beholder  marks  the 
greatest  difference  between  the  first  and  the  second  half 
of  the  century,  is  the  greatly  increased  intercourse  which 
now  exists  as  compared  with  the  earlier  years  of  our  cen- 
tury. This  intercourse  has  reacted  on  the  domain  of  2. 

Science  be- 
thought, and   produced    that   exchange   of   ideas   which  come  inter- 
national. 

promotes  more  rapid  progress.  It  hardly  belongs  to  the 
history  of  thought  to  analyse1  the  different  steps  by  which 
the  great  change  has  been  brought  about.  Still,  a  very 
superficial  glance  will  suffice  to  show  how  the  work  of 
bringing  about  an  international  exchange  of  ideas  has 
been  very  characteristically  divided  among  the  three 
nations  in  which  we  are  specially  interested.  It  was  not 
in  the  interest  of  thought,  of  science,  or  of  literature,  but 
rather  in  that  of  commerce  and  of  industry,  that  the 
modern  facilities  of  intercourse  and  exchange  were  in- 
vented and  introduced.2  We  shall  therefore  expect  to 

1  The  principal  dates  of  the  in-  [  1835.  The  first  German  railway 
troduction  of  steam  -  engines  and  was  opened  between  Niirenberg  and 
telegraphs  for  facilitating  communi-  Fiirth.  The  first  electric  telegraphs 
cation  are  as  follows  : —  for  public  use  were  almost  simul- 

1802.  The  tug  Charlotte  Dundas,  taneously  constructed  in  England, 
built  by  Symington,  was  tried  on  Germany,  and  the  United  States — 

the  Forth  and  Clyde  Canal.  '  the  first  successful  line  being  prob- 

1812.  Henry  Bell  built  the  Comet  ably  that  constructed  by  Wheat- 
with  side  paddle-wheels.  It  ran  on  stone  and  Cooke  between  1836  and 
the  Clyde  as  a  passenger  steamer.  1840.  The  first  Atlantic  cable  was 

1829.  George Stephenson's Rocket  begun  in  1857,  and  after  repeated 
was  tried  on  the  Stockton  and  Dar-  failures,  which  were  in  the  main 
lington  Railroad,  which  had  been  corrected  by  the  scientific  investi- 
begun  in  1821.  In  the  year  1829  gations  of  William  Thomson  (Lord 

the  Liverpool  and  Manchester  Rail-  .  Kelvin),  telegraphic  communication 

way  was  inaugurated.  |  with  America  was  permanently  es- 

1838.   The  first  steamboats,  Sirius       tablished  in  1 8  6  6 . 


and    Great   Western,    crossed    the 
Atlantic. 


2  This  remark  applies  fully  to  the 
railway  system,  but  scarcely  to  the 


1833.  A  comprehensive  system  of  development  of  the  electric  tele- 
railways  was  planned  by  the  French  graph,  which  was  first  actually  used 
and  Belgian  Governments.  for  scientific  purposes  by  Gauss  and 


304 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


find  them  originate  mainly  in  that  country  in  which 
those  larger  spheres  of  practical  work  had  grown  un- 
checked and  flourished — in  Great  Britain  and  its  exten- 
sive dependencies.  To  Germany,  on  the  other  side,  with 
its  fully  developed  system  of  learning,  we  are  indebted 
mainly  for  the  complete  recording,  registering,  and  analys- 
ing of  the  scientific  labours  of  the  whole  world.  To  France 


Weber  at  Gottingen  in  the  year 
1833.  The  documents  referring  to 
this  interesting  application  have 
recently  been  published  in  H. 
Weber's  biographical  notice  of  Wil- 
helm  Weber,  Breslau,  1893,  p.  25,  &c. 
We  read  there  that  soon  after  1830 
Gauss  had  been  occupied  with  re- 
ducing his  magnetical  measurements 
to  an  absolute  scale,  having  laid  his 
celebrated  paper,  "Intensitas  vis 
magnetic®  ad  mensuram  absolutam 
revocata,"  before  the  Gottingen  So- 
ciety in  December  of  1832.  He  had 
induced  Weber  to  take  up  similar 
investigations  at  the  Physical  In- 
stitute, which  was  situated  about  a 
mile  distant  from  Gauss's  Observa- 
tory. This  distance  was  found  to 
be  an  inconvenience,  and  in  order 
to  overcome  it,  the  first  longer  tele- 
graphic line  in  which  galvanic  cur- 
rents were  used,  and  which  had 
two  wires,  was  carried  overhead 
between  the  two  buildings,  and  the 
instruments  and  signalling  arrange- 
ments perfected  in  the  years  1833 
to  1836.  Both  Gauss  and  Weber 
were  well  aware  of  the  importance 
of  their  invention  for  practical  pur- 
poses. The  former  wrote  to  Olbers 
on  the  20th  November  1833:  "I 
do  not  know  whether  I  have  already 
written  to  you  regarding  a  magnifi- 
cent arrangement  which  we  have 
made  here.  It  is  a  galvanic  chain 
between  the  Observatory  and  the 
Physical  Institute,  carried  by  wires 
in  the  air  over  the  houses,  up  the 
Johannis  tower  and  down  again. 
The  whole  length  will  be  about 


8000  feet.  ...  I  have  devised  a 
simple  arrangement  by  which  I  can 
instantly  reverse  the  direction  of 
the  current,  which  I  call  a  com- 
mutator. .  .  .  We  have  already 
used  this  contrivance  for  telegraphic 
experiments,  which  succeed  very 
well  with  whole  words  and  short 
sentences.  ...  I  am  convinced 
that  by  using  sufficiently  strong 
wires  one  might  telegraph  instan- 
taneously in  this  manner  from 
Gottingen  to  Hanover  or  from 
Hanover  to  Bremen "  (see  Scher- 
ing's  address  on  the  occasion  of 
Gauss's  centenary,  Gottingen,  1877, 
p.  15,  &c.)  To  Schumacher,  6th 
August  1835,  Gauss  wrote  as  fol- 
lows: "With  a  budget  of  150 
thalers  [£22,  10s.]  annually  for 
Observatory  and  Magnetic  Insti- 
tute together,  really  extensive  trials 
cannot  of  course  be  made.  But 
could  thousands  of  thalers  be  be- 
stowed thereon,  I  think  that,  for 
instance,  electromagnetic  telegraphy 
might  be  carried  to  a  perfection  and 
to  dimensions  at  which  imagination 
almost  starts  back."  Gauss  esti- 
mates that  fifteen  millions  sterling 
of  copper  wire  would  suffice  to  reach 
the  antipodes,  and  he  says  signifi- 
cantly, "I  do  not  think  it  impos- 
sible to  invent  a  mechanism  by 
which  a  despatch  could  be  played 
off  almost  as  mechanically  as  a 
musical-box  plays  off  a  tune  when 
it  is  once  fixed  on  a  roller "  (see 
'  Brief wechsel  zwischen  Gauss  und 
Schumacher,'  ed.  Peters,  vol.  ii.  p. 
411,  &c.) 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF   NATURE.        305 

we  owe  the  first  beginnings  of  a  general  and  international 
system  of  units  and  measurements,  which,  like  the  com- 
mon Latin  tongue  in  former  centuries,  or  like  the  universal 
languages  of  algebra  or  of  music,  enables  us  to  express  the 
results  of  scientific  research  in  formulae  intelligible  every- 
where and  at  all  times,  without  laborious  translations  and 
time-absorbing  reductions. 

The  effect  of  these  international  labours  has  been  to        3. 

Disappear- 

destroy  the  clearly  marked  differences  of  national  thought.  an?.e  of . 

J  "  national 

At  least  iii  the  domain  of  science  the  peculiarities  of  the  dlfferences- 
French,  the  German,  and  the  English  schools  are  rapidly 
disappearing.  The  characteristics  of  national  thought 
still  exist ;  but  in  order  to  find  them  in  the  present  age 
we  should  have  to  study  the  deeper  philosophical  reason- 
ings, the  general  literature  and  the  artistic  efforts  of 
the  three  nations.  These  aspects  of  the  thought  of  our 
century  belong  to  later  portions  of  this  work.  I  hope 
there  to  take  up  many  of  the  threads  which  I  here  break 
off,  as  for  the  present  purpose  they  cannot  be  profitably 
continued.  To  separate  the  scientific  work  of  the  second 
half  of  the  century  according  to  countries  and  nations 
would  lead  to  unnecessary  repetition.  The  second  half  of 
the  century  sees  everywhere  in  the  domain  of  science  the 
dying  out  of  national  restrictions — in  every  country  the 
introduction  of  foreign  methods  and  foreign  models,  foreign 
institutions  and  foreign  apparatus.  The  establishment  of 
an  observatory  or  a  laboratory  in  our  age  lays  under  con- 
tribution almost  every  civilised  country  in  the  world,  and 
the  most  international  of  sciences — that  of  electricity — 
fixes  its  units  by  the  names  of  discoverers  of  many 
countries. 

VOL.  i.  u 


306  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

I  therefore  look  upon  the  spirit  of  exact  research  as 
thoroughly  domiciled  in  the  leading  countries  of  Europe 
during  the  second  half  of  the  century,  and  intend  in  the 
sequel  to  explain  more  precisely  the  different  views,  the 

4.  leading  ideas,  under  which  this  research  is  everywhere 

Special 

scientific      conducted.      These  leading  ideas  have  themselves  been 

ideas. 

more  clearly  brought  out  and  recognised  during  this 
period. 

The  narrow  spirit  of  the  Baconian  philosophy  which 
reigned  in  England,  the  vagueness  of  the  philosophy  of 
nature  which  reigned  in  Germany,  during  the  earlier 
decades  of  the  century,  have  disappeared  in  favour  of  the 
more  comprehensive  and  the  stricter  methods  taught  by 
Lavoisier,  by  Monge,  by  Laplace,  and  by  Cuvier  in  France. 
New  ideas  of  extensive  bearing  have  been  added,  and  in 
the  light  of  these  the  powers  and  the  limits  of  science 
have  been  more  correctly  recognised. 

To  some  of  my  readers  well-known  names  will  occur 
which  might  serve  as  guides  to  fix  these  leading  ideas, 

5.  under  the  influence  of  which  the  march  of  science  has 

Philosophy 

of  science,     proceeded:    Sir   John   Herschel,   Auguste   Comte,   John 
Stuart  Mill,  and  Whewell *  have  indeed  done  much  to 


1  Of  these  writings  the  earliest  is 
Sir  John  Herschel's  "Preliminary 
Discourse  on  the  Study  of  Natural 
Philosophy,"  which  appeared  in 
Lardner's  '  Cabinet  Cyclopedia '  in 
1831.  The  writings  of  William 
Whewell  on  the  'History 'and 'Phil- 
osophy of  the  Inductive  Sciences ' 
were  begun  about  the  same  time. 
They  were  planned  to  serve  three 
distinct  objects  —  to  give,  1st,  a 
philosophical  history  of  astronomy, 
mechanics,  physics,  chemistry,  and 
botany  ;  2nd,  an  analysis  of  the  na- 
ture of  induction  and  the  rules  of 


its  exercise  ;  and  3rd,  to  answer  the 
question  of  applying  inductive  pro- 
cesses to  other  than  material  sci- 
ences— as  philology,  art,  politics, 
and  morals  (see  'William  Whewell,' 
by  I.  Todhunter,  vol.  i.  p.  90). 
The  'History'  appeared  in  1837  in 
three  volumes,  a  second  edition  in 
1847,  a  third  in  1857  ;  the  'Philo- 
sophy' appeared  in  1840  in  two 
volumes,  a  second  edition  in  1847. 
In  the  course  of  its  execution  the 
original  plan  was  not  strictly  ad- 
hered to — the  scope  of  the  History 
was  enlarged  considerably,  and  the 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW    OF   NATURE.        307 


familiarise  the  unscientific  public  with  the  progress  of 
science  and  its  canons  of  thought.  And  it  would  thus 
appear  natural  to  resort  to  their  teaching  and  their  ex- 
planations. But  this  is  not  the  road  I  propose  to  follow. 
Whewell's  '  History  of  the  Inductive  Sciences,'  being  the 
first  attempt  to  compass  a  large  subject,  will,  like 
Montucla's  earlier  '  History  of  Mathematics,'  always  re- 
main a  standard  work.  It  was,  however,  written  at  a 
time  when  the  tendency  of  modern  scientific  thought  was 


Philosophy  was  broken  up  into 
different  parts.  Herschel  stands 
mainly  on  the  ground  of  Bacon's 
philosophy,  whereas  Whewell  starts 
with  the  remark  that  "  Bacon  only 
divined  how  sciences  might  be  con- 
structed," but  that  "  we  can  trace 
in  their  history  how  their  construc- 
tion hastaken  place" ;  that  "though 
Bacon's  general  maxims  still  guide 
and  animate  philosophical  inquirers, 
yet  that  his  views,  in  their  detail, 
have  all  turned  out  inapplicable." 
He  accordingly  aims  at  a  "New 
Organ  of  Bacon,  renovated  ac- 
cording to  our  advanced  intel- 
lectual position  and  office "  (Pre- 
face to  2nd  ed.  of  the  '  Philosophy,' 
1847).  In  the  exposition  of  his 
views  Whewell  was  greatly  influ- 
enced by  Kant's  philosophy.  He 
thus  searches  for  the  fundamental 
ideas  which  underlie  all  scientific 
reasoning  ;  for  ' '  besides  facts,  ideas 
are  an  indispensable  source  of  our 
knowledge."  The  historical  por- 
tions of  Whewell's  works  have  met 
with  great  appreciation  in  England 
and  Germany  even  from  those  who, 
like  Herschel  (see  the  review  in  the 
'Quarterly,'  June  1841)  and  Mill 
(see  '  Autobiography,'  p.  208),  could 
not  agree  with  his  philosophy. 
The  latter  has  been  eclipsed  by 
the  bolder  speculations  of  Auguste 
Comte,  whose  '  Philosophic  positive' 
appeared  in  six  volumes  between  the 


years  1830  and  1842  in  France. 
Still  more  than  Whewell  did  Comte 
emphasise  the  necessity  of  learning 
from  the  exact  sciences  how  to 
treat  economical  and  social  prob- 
lems in  a  methodical  manner. 
Instead  of  the  minute  and  fre- 
quently hesitating  elaborations  of 
Whewell,  we  find  in  Comte  the 
bold  generalisation  of  the  three 
stages  of  knowledge — the  theologi- 
cal, metaphysical,  and  positive, — 
which  forms  the  groundwork  of 
"  Positivism."  Of  more  permanent 
value  than  Whewell's  and  Comte's 
philosophies  are  the  investigations 
of  J.  Stuart  Mill,  who  in  his  '  Sys- 
tem of  Logic,  Ratiocinative  and  In- 
ductive' (1st  ed.,  1843),  has  laid 
the  foundation  for  all  subsequent 
treatises  on  this  subject,  and  whose 
thoroughgoing  empiricism  is  being 
more  and  more  adopted  by  scien- 
tific thinkers.  Like  Whewell  and 
Comte,  to  whom  he  acknowledges 
his  obligations  ('  Autobiog.,'  pp.  165, 
209,  &c.),  his  ultimate  object  was 
to  solve  the  question  "how  far  the 
methods  by  which  so  many  of  the 
laws  of  the  physical  world  have 
been  numbered  among  truths  irre- 
vocably acquired  and  universally 
assented  to,  can  be  made  instru- 
mental to  the  formation  of  a  similar 
body  of  received  doctrine  in  moral 
and  political  science "  (Preface  to 
1st  ed.) 


308  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

not  as  clear  as  it  has  become  since,  and  the  work  has 
also  been  superseded  by  more  detailed  labours,  espe- 
cially of  German  historians.1  The  '  Philosophy  of  the  In- 
ductive Sciences/  by  the  same  author,  was  written  with 
the  object  of  doing  something  towards  determining  the 
nature  and  conditions  of  human  knowledge,  and  had 
thus  a  philosophical  rather  than  a  historical  object  in 
view.  The  same  can  be  said  of  Mill's  '  Logic,'  of  Conite's 
'  Philosophic  positive,'  and  of  more  recent  works — such 
as  Jevons's  c  Principles  of  Science.'  They  form  an  im- 
portant section  of  the  philosophical  literature  of  our 
century,  and  on  future  occasions  I  shall  frequently  have 
to  refer  to  their  teaching.  At  present  I  am  not  about 
to  investigate  the  eternal  principles  of  correct  reason- 
ing, and  the  particular  methods  adopted,  consciously  or 
unconsciously,  by  scientific  writers  of  all  times.  "What 
I  desire  to  do  is,  to  enumerate  and  analyse  briefly  the 
changing  ideas,  the  general  views,  under  the  guidance 
of  which  scientific  work  has  progressed  in  the  course 
of  this  century.  No  doubt  the  same  object  was  before 

1  Besides  the  works  on  the  his-    j   of  the  '  Theory  of  Attraction  and 
tory  of  the   special    sciences   con-       Figure    of    the    Earth'    (2    vols., 


tained  in  the  Munich  Collection, 
'  Geschichte  der  Wissenschaf ten  in 
Deutschland,'  which  in  many  in- 
stances is  not  limited  to  German 
science  and  learning,  there  is  the 
unique  '  Geschichte  der  Chemie,' 
by  Hermann  Kopp  (Braunschweig, 
4  vols.,  1843-47),  the  '  Geschichte 
der  Physik,1  by  Rosenberger  (Braun- 


1873),  the  '  Calculus  of  Variations  ' 
(1861),  the  'Theory  of  Probability' 
(1865),  and  the  'Theory  of  Elastic- 
ity' (continued  by  K.  Pearson,  2 
vols.  in  3  parts,  1886-93).  They 
supply  the  want  of  a  good  history 
of  modern  mathematics,  which  does 
not  exist.  Lastly,  the  "  Deutsche 
Matheniatiker- Vereinigung  "  have 


schweig,    3    vols.,    1882-90),    and  i  published  in  their  Jahrbuch  valu- 

Haser's  '  Geschichte   der   Medicin  '  |  able  histories  of  special  branches  of 

(Wien,  1875-82,  3rd  ed.)     In  addi-  !  mathematics — notably  the  '  Theory 

tion  to  the  numerous  works  of  Ger-  j  of  Invariants !  by  Franz  Mayer,  and 

man  specialists,  I  must  mention  as  of  I  the  '  Modern  Theory  of  Functions ' 

the  first  importance  and  value  the  i  by  Brill  and  Xoether. 

histories  by  the  late  Isaac  Todhunter  I 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW    OF   NATURE. 


309 


the    mind    of    Whewell    when,    after    writing    his    his-        e. 


torical  work,  he  attempted  in  the  philosophical  sequel  'History, 
to  abstract  the  general  ideas  which  have  led  scientific  os°Phy-' 
research  ;  but  it  is  instructive  for  our  present  purpose 
to  note  how,  writing  about  the  middle  of  the  century, 
he  hardly  brought  out  any  of  those  principles  which 
in  the  course  of  its  second  half  have  turned  out  to 
be  fruitful,  and  have  almost  become  watchwords  of 
popular  science.  In  the  year  1857,  the  date  of  the 
publication  of  the  latest  editions  of  Whewell's  works, 
nothing  was  popularly  known  of  energy,  its  conserva- 
tion and  dissipation,  —  nothing  of  the  variation  of  species, 
and  the  evolution  of  organic  forms,  —  nothing  of  the 
mechanical  theory  of  heat  or  of  that  of  gases  —  of 
absolute  measurements  and  absolute  temperature  ;  even 
the  cellular  theory  seems  to  have  been  popular  only  in 
Germany.  And  yet  all  the  problems  denoted  by  these 
now  popular  terms  were  then  occupying,  or  had  for  many 
years  occupied,  the  leading  thinkers  of  that  period.  But 
we  find  no  mention  of  them  in  Whewell's  works.1  So 


1  The  dates  of  the  birth  of  these 
leading  ideas  of  the  second  half  of 
our  century  are  approximately  as 
follows  : — 

Absolute  measurements  were 
started  by  Gauss  about  1830,  and 
the  scheme  published  in  1833  in 
his  memoir,  '  Intensitas  vis  magne- 
tics terrestris  ad  mensuram  absolu- 
tam  revocata.'  They  were  extended 
to  electrical  phenomena  by  Weber  in 
his  'Electrodynamische  Maasbestim- 
muugen,' 1846.  The  absolute  scale 
of  temperature  was  introduced  by 
William  Thomson  in  1848. 

The  cellular  theory  was  pro- 
pounded by  Schleiden  in  1838,  and 


extended  to  animal  structures  by 
Schwann  in  1839  ;  the  term  "pro- 
toplasm "  was  introduced  by  Mohl 
in  1846. 

The  mechanical  theory  of  heat 
dates  from  Mayer's  and  Joule's  de- 
terminations of  the  equivalent  of 
heat  in  1842  and  1843. 

The  doctrine  of  the  conservation 
of  energy  dates  from  Helmholtz's 
memoir,  '  Ueber  die  Erhaltung  der 
Kraft,'  in  1847  ;  that  of  dissipation 
of  energy  from  William  Thomson's 
paper  "  On  a  Universal  Tendency 
in  Nature  to  the  Dissipation  of 
Mechanical  Energy,"  1852  ;  it  was 
prepared  by  Watt's  and  Poncelet's 


310 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


little  was  the  foremost  champion  of  inductive  thought 
able  to  discern  the  tendencies  of  his  age :  a  warning  to 
those  who  attempt  to  recognise  the  aims  of  contemporary 
thought.1 

It  is  not,  then,  to  the  philosophical  writers  that  I  shall 
apply  in  order  to  trace  the  leading  directions  of  scientific 


definitions  of  horse-power  and  work 
(1826),  which  Whewell  does  not 
mention. 

The  mechanical  theory  of  gases — 
not  to  mention  the  older  specula- 
tions of  Daniel  Bernoulli  —  dates 
from  ATOgadro's  and  Ampere's 
hypothesis,  published  in  1811, 
"  that  all  gaseous  bodies,  under  the 
same  physical  conditions,  contain 
the  same  number  of  units,"  from 
Herapath  (1821)  and  Joule  (1851). 

On  WhewelTs  position  with  regard 
to  the  question  of  the  origin  and 
variation  of  species,  then  already 
ventilated  by  Lyell,  see  '  History  of 
Induct.  ScL,'  vol.  iii.  p.  489,  &c. 
(3rd  ed. ),  and  Huxley's  remarks  in 
the  '  Life  of  Charles  Darwin,'  vol. 
ii.  p.  192,  &c.  Wallace's  essay  '  On 
the  Law  which  has  regulated  the 
Introduction  of  New  Species'  was 
published  in  1858  along  with  Dar- 
win's preliminary  statement  of  his 
views. 

We  might  form  a  whole  catalogue 
of  scientific  terms,  some  of  them 
by  no  means  of  recent  origin, 
which  are  wanting  in  WhewelTs 
books,  but  which  now  govern  scien- 
tific progress :  such  are  energy, 
work,  action  and  efficiency,  absol- 
ute measurement,  to  mention  only 
physical  terms.  The  general  ideas 
upon  which  he  himself  lavs  some 
stress,  such  as  those  of  polarity  and 
symmetry,  appear  on  the  other 
hand  to  be  vague  generalisations, 
which  have  frequently  led  people 
astray. 

1  "  It  is  a  remarkable  evidence  of 


the  greatness  of  the  progress  which 
has  been  effected  in  our  time,  that 
even  the  second  edition  of  the 
'  History  of  the  Inductive  Scien- 
ces,' which  was  published  in  1546, 
contains  no  allusion  to  the  publi- 
cation in  1843  of  the  first  of  the 
series  of  experiments  by  which  the 
mechanical  equivalent  of  heat  was 
correctly  ascertained.  Such  a  fail- 
ure on  the  part  of  a  contemporary, 
of  great  acquirements  and  remark- 
able intellectual  powers,  to  read 
the  signs  of  the  times,  is  a  lesson 
and  a  warning  worthy  of  being 
deeply  pondered  by  any  one  who 
attempts  to  prognosticate  the 
course  of  scientific  progress"  Hux- 
ley in  Ward's  '  Reign  of  Queen  Vic- 
toria," vol.  ii.  p.  355}.  The  same 
writer  has  pointed  out  how  Au- 
guste  Comte  was  still  more  un- 
fortunate in  his  opinions  on  con- 
temporary science.  "  What  struck 
me  was  his  want  of  apprehension 
of  the  great  features  of  science ; 
his  strange  mistakes  as  to  the 
merits  of  his  scientific  contempor- 
aries ;  and  his  ludicrously  erroneous 
notions  about  the  part  which  some 
of  the  scientific  doctrines  current 
in  his  time  were  destined  to  play  in 
the  future"  (''Scientific  Aspects  of 
Positivism."  'Lay  Sermons,'  1S91, 
p.  130).  He  then  goes  on  to  show 
how  Comte  treated  the  undulatory 
theory  with  contempt,  extolled 
Gall,  depreciated  Cuvier,  and  spoke 
of  the  "abuse  of  microscopic  in- 
vestigations "  (ibid.,  p.  134). 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW    OF    NATURE.        311 

thought    in    our   century :    their    position    towards   this 
thought  is  indeed  instructive,  but  it  is  frequently  unsafe. 

Philosophical  reasoning  either  precedes  or  succeeds  7. 
the  labours  of  the  scientific  thinker ;  it  rarely  accom-  and  science. 
panics  them.  In  the  history  of  earlier  times,  during  the 
first  centuries  of  the  modern  period,  we  find  some  of  the 
foremost  philosophers,  such  as  Descartes,  Bacon,  Leibniz, 
occupied  in  attempting  to  lay  down  the  correct  lines  on 
which  science  should  proceed,  or  to  find  general  ideas 
which  could  serve  as  supreme  principles  of  scientific 
truth.  It  is  a  rare  thing  to  find  that  they  have  succeeded 
in  either  of  these  attempts.  In  more  modern  times, 
ever  since  Locke  started  on  a  different  track,  it  has  been, 
especially  in  this  country,  the  endeavour  of  philosophers 
to  abstract  out  of  the  existing  volumes  of  scientific  re- 
search the  leading  ideas  which  have  proved  so  helpful, 
and  to  explain  their  origin,  their  bearing,  and  their  value. 
Perhaps  they  have  been  more  successful  than  their  pre- 
decessors :  it  has,  however,  frequently  happened  to  them, 
that  whilst  they  were  elaborately  analysing  some  process 
of  reasoning,  or  some  prevailing  scientific  principle, 
science  has  meanwhile  adopted  some  entirely  different 
line,  and  presented  an  entirely  unexpected  development. 

In  this  respect  they  resemble  that  school  of  historical 
politicians  which  in  the  middle  of  our  century  in  Ger- 
many *  attempted  to  read  the  signs  of  the  times,  and  to 


1  This  is  the  school  represented  by 
the  historians  Dahlmann  and  Ger- 
vinus.  A  good  account,  with  a 
somewhat  severe  criticism  of  the 
aims  of  this  school,  will  be  found 
in  Karl  Hillebrand,  '  Zeiten,  Volker 
und  Menschen,'  vol.  ii.  pp.  205-290. 
' '  The  State  and  Literature  had 


growii  in  Germany  alongside  of 
each  other  without  coming  into 
contact,  the  former  active,  reticent, 
modest,  the  latter  declaiming, 
noisy,  pretentious.  It  appeared  as 
if  all  our  life  had  become  intellect- 
ual ;  Gerviuus  himself  thought  so 
and  blamed  us.  In  reality  it  was 


312 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


very 
ancient. 


prescribe  the  lines  on  which  the  desired  unification  of  the 
nation  could  be  secured.  Events  took  their  own  course, 
and  the  great  statesman  who  was  the  central  figure  of  the 
new  era  of  European  history  may  be  excused  the  scorn 
with  which  he  has  sometimes  treated  these  theoretical 
politicians. 
s.  The  leading  ideas  which  I  select  as  marking  the  progress 

Leading 

scientific      of  scientific  research  in  our  century  have,  with  few  excep- 

ideas  mostly 

tions,  hardly  been  discoveries  or  inventions  of  this  age. 
Some  of  them  are  very  old.  The  ideas  of  attraction, 
which  in  the  hands  of  Newton  and  Laplace  have  led  to 
such  remarkable  results,  are  of  great  age,  and  were 
familiar  to  the  philosophers  of  Greece  and  Home ;  the 
same  can  be  said  of  the  atomic  theory,  which  in  the 
hands  of  Dalton  became  such  a  powerful  instrument. 
The  principles  of  energy  and  its  conservation  can  be 
traced  back  to  the  writings  of  Newton  and  Leibniz,  and 
even  to  earlier  thinkers.  The  same  may  be  said  of  the 
modern  ideas  on  heat,  of  the  molecular  theory  of  gases, 
and  even  of  Lord  Kelvin's  vortices ;  whilst  the  views 
which  through  Darwin  have  revolutionised  the  natural 
sciences  have  been  traced  in  the  suggestions  of  much  ear- 


not  so.  When  the  professoi's  turned 
their  backs  on  science  in  order  to 
turn  to  politics,  they  imagined  pol- 
itics were  now  only  beginning : 
with  the  wonted  pride  of  learning 
they  saw  in  the  administrative 
class  only  labourers  and  clerks  ;  for 
to  them  parliaments  and  freedom 
of  the  press  were  identical  with 
politics.  The  mouthpiece  of  Ger- 
many was  in  the  universities,  as 
that  of  France  was  at  the  bar; 
they  only  heard  each  other  :  was 
it  therefore  unnatural  if  they 


thought  the  German  professors 
composed  the  German  nation,  as 
the  French  lawyers  formed  the 
French  nation  ?  And  indeed  pub- 
lic opinion  in  Germany  was  that  of 
the  professors.  .  .  .  The  learned 
newspaper  writers  imagined  the 
spirit  of  the  age  spake  in  them ; 
no  wonder  that  they  overestimated 
the  importance  of  this  spirit  and  of 
this  so-called  public  opinion  "  (ibid., 
p.  254).  See  also  Treitschke's 
'Deutsche  Geschichte,'  vol.  v.  p. 
408,  &c. 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        313 

Her  writers.  Elaborate  claims  to  priority  have  thus  been 
set  up  for  persons  to  whom  it  is  said  the  credit  of  modern 
discoveries  should  be  given.  I  do  not  intend  to  contribute 
to  this  controversial  literature,  except  by  a  general  remark, 
which  will  explain  how  it  has  come  to  pass  that  ideas  and 
principles  now  recognised  as  useful  instruments  of  thought 
and  research  have  only  recently  attained  this  importance, 
while  they  have  frequently  been  the  property  of  many 
ages  of  philosophical  thought,  and  familiar  even  to  the 
writers  of  antiquity.  It  is  the  scientific  method,  the  exact 
statement,  which  was  wanting,  and  which  raises  the  vague 
guesses  of  the  philosophical  or  the  dreams  of  the  poetic 
mind  to  the  rank  of  definite  canons  of  thought,  capable  of 
precise  expression,  of  mathematical  analysis,  and  of  exact 
verification.  Obscure  notions  of  the  attractive  and  re- 
pulsive forces  of  nature  have  floated  before  the  minds  of 
philosophers  since  the  time  of  Empedocles,  but  they  did 
not  become  useful  to  science  till  Galileo  and  Newton  took 
the  first  step  to  measure  the  intensity  of  those  forces. 
Lucretius's  poem  introduces  to  us  the  early  speculations 
on  the  atomic  constitution  of  matter,  but  the  hypotheses 
of  his  school  only  led  to  real  knowledge  of  the  things  of 
nature  when  Dalton,  following  Lavoisier  and  Eichter,  re- 
duced this  idea  to  definite  numbers ;  still  more  so  when, 
through  the  law  of  Avogadro  and  Ampere,  and  the  calcu- 
lations of  Joule,  Clausius,  and  Thomson,  the  velocities,  the 
number,  and  sizes  of  atoms  became  calculable  and  measur- 
able quantities.  Descartes,  and  after  him  Malebranche, 
filled  space  with  vortices  which  were  to  explain  the  con- 
stitution of  matter  and  the  movements  of  its  parts;  but 
the  notion  was  abandoned  and  ridiculed  till  Helmholtz 


314  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

and  Thomson  approached  the  subject  with  mathematical 
analysis  and  calculated  the  properties  of  vortex  motion. 

Heraclitus  proclaimed,  six  hundred  years  before  the 
Christian  era,  the  theory  that  everything  moves  or  flows ; 
but  not  till  this  century  was  the  attempt  made  to  work 
out  the  definite  hypothesis  of  Daniel  Bernoulli,  and 
to  explain  the  properties  of  bodies,  apparently  at  rest — 
the  pressure  of  gases,  or  the  phenomena  of  elasticity — 
by  assuming  a  hidden  motion  of  the  imperceptible  portions 
of  matter.  The  same  fate  of  lying  dormant  for  ages  at- 
9.  taches  to  the  suggestive  ideas  of  many  thinkers.  In  every 

Mathemati- 
cal spirit,      case    the   awakening    touch   has   been  the  mathematical 

spirit,  the  attempt  to  count,  to  measure,  or  to  calculate. 
What  to  the  poet  or  the  seer  may  appear  to  be  the 
very  death  of  all  his  poetry  and  all  his  visions — the  cold 
touch  of  the  calculating  mind, — this  has  proved  to  be  the 
spell  by  which  knowledge  has  been  born,  by  which  new 
sciences  have  been  created,  and  hundreds  of  definite  prob- 
lems put  before  the  minds  and  into  the  hands  of  diligent 
students.  It  is  the  geometrical  figure,  the  dry  algebraical 
formula,  which  transforms  the  vague  reasoning  of  the 
philosopher  into  a  tangible  and  manageable  conception ; 
which  represents,  though  it  does  not  fully  describe,  which 
corresponds  to,  though  it  does  not  explain,  the  things  and 
processes  of  nature :  this  clothes  the  fruitful,  but  other- 
wise indefinite,  ideas  in  such  a  form  that  the  strict  logical 
methods  of  thought  can  be  applied,  that  the  human  mind 
can  in  its  inner  chamber  evolve  a  train  of  reasoning  the 
result  of  which  corresponds  to  the  phenomena  of  the  outer 
world.  By  such  processes  did  Gauss  and  Leverrier  suc- 
ceed in  tracing  the  lines  in  the  heavens  on  which  invisible 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        315 


stars  were  speeding  through  the  universe ;  without  them 
these  objects  of  nature  would  probably  never  have  been 
seen,  and  if  seen,  they  would  not  have  been  recognised. 
Similar,  and  still  more  intricate,  reasonings  permitted 
Mendele'eff  *  to  arrange  in  geometrical  order  the  several 
elements  or  simple  substances  out  of  which  matter  is 
compounded,  and  to  point  to  the  vacant  places  on  the 
chart,  some  of  which  have  since  been  filled  up  by  new 
discoveries.  Thus  it  has  also  been  shown  that  the  ranges 
of  temperature  cannot  be  extended  indefinitely  in  both 
directions — viz.,  those  of  heat  and  cold — but  that  the 
latter  possesses  a  zero  point,  representing  the  complete 
absence  of  motion.2 


1  The    periodic    arrangement    of 
the  elements,  according  to  which, 
with  increasing  atomic  or  combining 
numbers,  the  same  properties — such 
as   density,   fusibility,  optical   and 
electric  qualities,  and  formation  of 
oxides,  &c. — recur  in  periods  which 
are  at  least  approximately  fixed,  so 
that   they  can   be   represented  by 
curves,  dates  from  the  year  1869, 
when   D.    Mendeleeff    and    Lothar 
Meyer  published  almost  simultane-  - 
ously  their  classification  of  the  ele- 
ments.     Newlands  seems  to  have 
indicated   some   of    these   facts   as 
early    as    1864.      Mendeleeff   pre- 
dicted the  properties  of  a  missing 
element,  found  to  be  those  of  scan- 
dium, which  Nilson  discovered  ten 
years  later.     The  same  applies  to 
the  two  other  elements  which  were 
subsequently  discovered  by  Lecocq 
de  Boisbaudran  (1878,  gallium)  and 
Winkler  (1886,  germanium),  and  in 
1894  the  newly  discovered  element 
argon   was  found  to  fill  a  vacant 
place  in  the  plan. 

2  The  zero  point  of  temperature 
was  originally  a  purely  mathemati- 
cal quantity  suggested  by  the  for- 


mula which  gives  the  expansion  of 
air  in  the  air  thermometer  as  de- 
pendent on  the  temperature.  The 
ideal,  not  realisable,  temperature 
at  which,  according  to  the  for- 
mula, the  volume  of  air  would  be 
nothing,  was  fixed  by  calculation  at 
459°'13  Fahr.  or  272° '85  Centi- 
grade. The  real  physical,  not  mere- 
ly mathematical,  meaning  of  the 
absolute  scale  of  temperature  with 
its  zero  point  was  only  revealed 
when,  through  Carnot  and  Thom- 
son, it  was  established  that  every 
degree  of  temperature  has  an  assign- 
able value  for  doing  work,  and  when 
a  scale  of  thermometry  was  sug- 
gested by  Thomson  (1848)  in  which 
every  one  degree  had  the  same 
dynamical  value,  100°  in  it  cor- 
responding to  the  100°  Centigrade 
in  the  air  thermometer.  It  was 
then  found  that  the  two  scales — 
that  of  the  air  thermometer  and 
that  measuring  the  dynamical  value 
of  temperature — agreed  almost  ex- 
actly. The  number  273°  Cent,  thus 
acquired  a  physical  meaning  (see 
Clerk  Maxwell,  'Heat,'  8th  ed., 
pp.  49,  159,  and  215).  Another 


316 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


By  drawing  curves  on  paper  which  correspond  to  the 
thermal  properties  of  various  substances,  the  conditions 
have  been  defined  beforehand  under  which  gaseous  bodies 
like  oxygen,  hydrogen,  nitrogen,  or  common  atmospheric 
air  can  be  reduced  to  liquid  and  solid  bodies,  upsetting 
the  notions  of  the  last  generation,  which  looked  upon 
these  substances  as  permanent  gases.1  If  the  mathe- 
matical formula  has  killed,  or  failed  to  grasp,  the  true 
life  of  nature,  that  which  to  the  poet  and  the  philosopher 
will  always  be  the  feature  of  supremest  interest,  it  has  on 
the  other  side  given  birth  to  that  new  life  of  ideas  which 
in  our  reasoning  minds  serve  as  the  images  of  things 


example  of  a  purely  mathematical 
quantity  which,  suggested  originally 
by  a  formula,  acquired  later  a  physi- 
cal meaning,  is  that  of  the  potential 
function,  used  first  by  Lagrange  as 
a  simplification  in  calculating  the 
forces  of  a  disturbing  planet,  and 
termed  by  Laplace  ' '  a  cause  de  son 
utilite,  une  veritable  decouverte" 
('Mec.  eel.,'  v.  livre  xv.  chap.  i. ) 
This  function,  which  has  the  pro- 
perty that  by  a  simple  differentia- 
tion the  component  of  the  force  in 
any  direction  is  found,  acquired  a 
physical  meaning  as  the  quantity, 
the  change  of  which  measures  the 
work  required  to  move  a  unit  of 
matter  from  one  point  to  another 
(see  Thomson  and  Tait,  '  Natural 
Philosophy,'  vol.  L  2,  p.  29).  Other 
examples  of  purely  mathematical 
quantities  which  reveal  physical 
properties  are  Hamilton's  "char- 
acteristic function "  (see  Tait, 
"Mechanics,"  'Ency.  Brit.,'  9th 
ed.,  p.  749),  Rankine's  "  Thermo- 
dynamic  function,"  called  by  Clau- 
sius  "Entropy"  (see  Maxwell, 
'Heat,'  pp.  162,  189) :  it  measures 
the  unavailable  energy  of  a  system. 
1  Thomas  Andrews  (1813-85)  took 
up  the  experiments  begun  by  Cag- 


niard  -  Latour  in  1822,  and  ex- 
plained how  it  comes  about  that  a 
gas  remains  incondensable  however 
great  the  pressure  may  be,  pro- 
vided the  temperature  exceeds 
what  he  termed  the  "critical  tem- 
perature," which  is  different  for 
different  gases.  He  accompanied 
his  statements,  which  were  first 
published  in  the  3rd  edition  of 
Miller's  Chemical  Physics,  by  curves 
representing  the  behaviour  of  at- 
mospheric air  and  of  carbonic  acid, 
the  latter  being  a  condensable  gas, 
and  he  suggested  in  1872  that  the 
so-called  permanent  gases  had  a 
critical  point  far  below  the  lowest 
known  temperatures,  and  that  this 
was  the  reason  why  their  lique- 
faction had  not  yet  been  achieved. 
Two  physicists,  Cailletet  and  Pictet, 
took  up  these  suggestions ;  after 
various  trials  they  succeeded  inde- 
pendently in  1877  in  liquefying 
several  of  the  permanent  gases, 
notably  oxygen  and  nitrogen. 
These  have  been  followed  by  all 
the  other  permanent  gases,  includ- 
ing atmospheric  air,  of  which  large 
quantities  can  now  be  prepared  in 
a  liquefied  form. 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF   NATURE.        317 

natural,  and  allow  us  to  make  them  subservient  to  our 
purposes. 

Whoever  grasps  the  significance  of  the  change  which        10. 

When  first 

the  exact  or  mathematical  treatment  of  knowledge  has  introduced 

into  science. 

worked  in  our  life  and  thought,  will  readily  place  that 
name  at  the  entrance  of  a  history  of  modern  thought, 
which  is  identified  with  a  few  simple  mathematical  for- 
mulae, by  which  ever  since  his  time  the  progress  of  science 
has  been  guided.  Though  belonging  to  an  earlier  period, 
the  full  meaning  of  Newton's  work  has  only  been  recog- 
nised in  the  course  of  our  century.  In  fact  the  New- 
tonian philosophy  can  be  said  to  have  governed  at  least 
one  entire  section  of  the  scientific  research  of  the  first 
half  of  this  period :  only  in  the  second  half  of  the  period 
have  we  succeeded  in  defining  more  clearly  the  direction 
in  which  Newton's  views  require  to  be  extended  or  modi- 
fied. Newton's  greatest  achievement  was  to  combine  the 
purely  mechanical  laws  which  Galileo  and  Huygens  had 
established  with  the  purely  physical  relations  which 
Kepler — following  Copernicus  and  Tycho — had  discovered 
in  the  planetary  motions,  and  to  abstract  in  so  doing 
the  general  formula  of  universal  attraction  or  gravitation. 
Newton  looked  upon  the  motion  of  the  moon  round  the 
earth,  or  the  planets  round  the  sun,  as  examples  on  a 
large  scale  of  the  motion  of  falling  bodies — studied  by 
Galileo — on  the  surface  of  the  earth.  Delayed  in  the 
publication  of  this  simple  rule  of  planetary  motion 
through  the  absence  of  correct  measurements,  and  through 
the  necessity  of  inventing  a  new  calculus  by  which  the 
mathematical  results  of  the  formula  could  be  ascertained, 
Newton  did  not  publish  his  'Principia'  till  1687.  The 


318 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


11. 

Newton's 


work,  however,  was  conceived  in  the  highest  philosophic 

...  ,  . 

spirit,  inasmuch  as  the  enunciation  of  the  so-called  law  of 
gravitation  required  the  clear  expression  of  the  general 
laws  of  motion.  In  the  first  and  second  parts  of  the 
work  the  discoveries  of  Galileo  and  Huygens  were  ab- 
sorbed, generalised,  and  restated  in  such  terms  as  have  up 
to  our  age  been  considered  sufficient  to  form  the  basis  for 
all  purely  mechanical  reasoning.1  In  the  latter  part  the 
new  rule,  corresponding  to  Kepler's  empirical  laws,  is 
represented  as  the  key  to  a  system  of  the  universe.  The 
great  outlines  of  this  system  are  boldly  drawn,  and  the 
working  out  of  it  is  left  as  the  great  bequest  of  Newton 
to  his  successors.  At  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century, 


1  The  most  recent  historian  of 
the  subject  is  Prof.  Ernst  Mach  of 
Prague,  whose  '  Mechanik  in  ihrer 
Entwickelung,  historisch  -  kritisch 
dargestellt,'  2nd  ed.,  1889,  I  cannot 
praise  too  highly.  It  has  been 
translated  into  English  by  M'Cor- 
mack  (Chicago  and  London,  1893). 
Referring  to  Newton,  he  says : 
"  Newton  has  with  regard  to  our 
subject  two  great  merits.  Firstly, 
he  has  greatly  enlarged  the  hori- 
zon of  mechanical  physics  through 
the  discovery  of  universal  gravi- 
tation. Further,  he  has  also  com- 
pleted the  enunciation  of  the  prin- 
ciples of  mechanics  as  we  now  ac- 
cept them.  After  him  an  essen- 
tially new  principle  has  not  been 
established.  What  after  him  has 
been  done  in  mechanics  refers  to 
the  deductive,  formal,  and  mathe- 
matical development  of  mechanics 
on  the  ground  of  Newton's  prin- 
ciples" (p.  174).  "Newton's  prin- 
ciples are  sufficient  without  the 
introduction  of  any  new  principle 
to  clear  up  every  mechanical  prob- 
lem which  may  present  itself,  be 


it  one  of  statics  or  of  dynamics. 
If  difficulties  present  themselves, 
they  are  always  only  mathematical, 
formal,  not  fundamental "  (p.  239). 
"All  important  mathematical  ex- 
pressions of  modern  mechanics  were 
already  found  and  used  in  the  age 
of  Galileo  and  Newton.  The  spe- 
cial names  .  .  .  have  sometimes 
been  fixed  much  later.  Still  later 
came  the  adoption  of  uniform 
measures,  and  this  process  is  even 
yet  incomplete  "  (p.  252).  In  this 
country  it  is  one  of  the  great  mer- 
its of  Thomson  and  Tait's  'Nat- 
ural Philosophy '  that  they  "  re- 
stored "  the  teaching  of  mechanics 
and  placed  it  on  the  original  foun- 
dations afforded  by  Newton's  laws 
of  motion,  in  his  own  words,  as 
"every  attempt  that  has  been 
made  to  supersede  them  has  ended 
in  utter  failure"  (Preface),  and, 
though  they  "are  only  tempor- 
arily the  best,"  there  does  not 
exist,  "as  yet,  anything  nearly  as 
good  "  (Tait  in  article  "  Mechanics," 
'Ency.  Brit.,'  9th  ed.,  p.  749). 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        319 

after  many  able  mathematicians  and  observers  had  gen- 
erally investigated  the  numberless  problems  contained  in 
the  '  Principia,'  Laplace  published  his  '  Exposition  du 
Systeme  du  Monde,'  followed  in  the  course  of  the  first 
quarter  of  this  century  by  the  '  Mecanique  celeste ' ; l  and 
at  the  close  of  the  present  century  the  most  learned 
astronomer  of  the  age  could  say  that  the  '  Principia ' 
still  formed  the  sole  foundation  of  all  investigations  in 
that  domain.2 

It  is  interesting  to  see  how  in  a  simple  formula  the       12. 

...  Thegravita- 

mathematician  is  able  to  condense  an  almost  immeasur-  won  for- 
mula. 

able  volume  of  thought,  bringing  the  theory  and  the 
observations  of  past  ages  to  a  focus  from  which  new  lines 
of  thought  diverge  in  many  directions.  Every  mathe- 


1  The  '  Exposition  du  Systeme 
du  Monde'  appeared,  1796,  in  2 
vols.  8vo :  the  first  and  second 
volume  of  the  '  Mecanique  celeste,' 


gravitation,"  which  was  given  by 
Newton  in  such  a  way  that  the 
action  of  one  or  more  third  (dis- 
turbing) bodies  could  be  taken  into 


1799,  4to  ;  the  third,  1802  ;  the  j  account,  dealing  thus  with  the  case 
fourth,  1805  ;  the  last,  1825.  Be-  j  of  nature,  which  had  in  the  first 
fore  publishing  this  work,  which  instance  presented  itself  in  treating 
has  been  termed  a  second  edition  !  of  the  complex  motion  of  the  moon, 
of  the  '  Principia,'  Laplace  had  ;  Laplace  himself,  who  in  number- 
himself  during  thirty  years  assisted  '  less  passages  of  his  works  re- 
in dispelling  the  last  doubts  as  to  curs  to  the  discoveries  of  Newton, 
the  sufficiency  of  the  doctrine  of  announced  the  object  of  the  '  Me- 
universal  gravitation  to  explain  all  canique  celeste  '  to  be  the  treat- 
cosmical  phenomena;  and  he  had  ment  of  astronomy  "as  a  great 
especially  brought  the  investiga-  ,  problem  of  mechanics,  from  which 
tions  of  Clairaut,  Euler,  d'Alem-  it  was  important  to  banish  as  much 
bert,  Lambert,  and  Lagrange  to  a  as  possible  all  empiricism,"  and  to 
final  result  by  publishing  in  sue-  j  perfect  it  so  as  "to  borrow  from 
cessive  memoirs  between  1773  and  f  observation  only  the  most  indis- 
1786  the  doctrine  of  "the  stability  pensable  data"  ('  Mec.  c6\.,'  vol.  L 


of  the  system  of  the  universe," 
based  upon  the  invariability  of  the 
major  axes  and  the  periods  of  re- 
volution of  the  planetary  orbits. 
He  and  his  predecessors  also  ex- 
tended the  solution  of  the  problem 
"to  find  the  orbit  of  two  bodies, 
acting  under  the  law  of  mutual 


introd. ) 

2  The  late  Professor  Rudolf  Wolf 
of  Zurich,  whose  '  Handbuch  der 
Astronomic,  ihrer  Geschichte  und 
Litteratur,'  2  vols.,  1890-93,  as  well 
as  his  earlier  '  Geschichte  der  As- 
tronomic,' Miinchen,  1877, 1  warmly 
recommend. 


320 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


matical  formula  which  expresses  the  existing  relations 
of  natural  things  acts  in  a  similar  way,  but  probably  few, 
if  any,  subsequent  discoveries  have  given  scientific  minds 
so  much  fruitful  work  to  do  as  the  gravitation  formula. 
An  analysis  of  it  will  serve  us  as  a  guide  through  a  very 
large  portion  of  the  scientific  work  of  our  period :  it  will 
serve  also  as  an  example  of  the  great  service  which  the 
mathematical  mode  of  dealing  with  conceptions  renders  to 
the  progress  of  science  and  of  thought. 

The  so-called  law  of  gravitation  states  that  every  two 
portions  of  matter,  placed  at  a  distance  from  each  other, 
exert  on  each  other  an  attractive  force,1  which  depends 
on  the  masses  of  each,  and  on  their  distance  from 
each  other.  The  attractive  force  varies  in  the  direct 
proportion  of  the  mass  of  each,  and  in  the  inverse 
duplicate  ratio  of  the  distance.  Three  distinct  lines  of 


1  The  gravitation  formula  gives 
no  indication  of  the  actual  or  abso- 
lute amount  of  the  force  in  ques- 
tion ;  it  only  establishes  a  relation. 
It  was  fully  three-quarters  of  a 
century  after  the  publication  of  the 
'  Principia '  that  experiments  were 
suggested  in  order  to  determine  the 
actual  magnitude  of  the  force  of 
gravitation — i.e.,  the  constant  c  in 

the  formula  f=c    \  .     Michell  in 

7~" 

1768  devised  an  apparatus,  em- 
ployed later  (1797)  by  Cavendish, 
and  Maskelyne  made  measurements 
towards  the  end  of  the  last  century. 
More  and  more  accurate  determin- 
ations were  made  all  through  the 
present  century,  and  latterly  by 
Prof.  Boys.  Few  persons  have  an 
idea  of  the  extreme  feebleness  of  the 
force,  which  nevertheless,  through 
the  magnitude  of  the  earth,  ac- 
quires in  our  daily  experience  such 
ormidable  proportions.  As  it  ia 


desirable,  in  accordance  with  one  of 
the  principal  scientific  tendencies  of 
our  age,  to  place  the  knowledge  of 
absolute  physical  quantities  in  the 
place  of  merely  relative  numbers, 
I  mention  here  that  the  force  with 
which  two  units  of  matter  (i.e.,  2 
grammes)  placed  at  unit  distance 
(i.e.,  1  centimetre)  apart  attract 
each  other  is  such  that  they  would 
approach  each  other  with  a  velo- 
city of  nearly  7  hundred  millionths 
of  a  centimetre  in  the  first  second 
of  time.  As  a  pound  is  a  more 
familiar  quantity,  we  may  also  say 
that  two  masses,  each  containing 
415,000  tons  of  matter,  and  situ- 
ated at  a  distance  of  one  statute 
mile  apart,  will  attract  each  other 
with  the  force  of  1  Ib.  (see  Sir 
R.  S.  Ball,  'Ency.  Brit,'  9th  ed., 
art.  "  Gravitation  ")•  See  also  Sir 
R.  S.  Ball,  'The  Story  of  the 
Heavens,'  p.  106,  and  Prof.  Boys 
in  'Nature,'  vol.  50,  p.  330,  &c. 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        321 


scientific  research  are  involved  and  opened  out  by  this 
statement. 

First,  There  is  the  purely  theoretical  task  of  defining 
clearly  what  is  meant  by  the  different  words  which  are 
used,  and  which  in  the  formula  are  expressed  in  algebraic 
symbols.  What  is  the  definition  of  force,  what  of  mass, 
what  of  distance  ?  The  '  Principia '  give  Newton's  defi- 
nitions.1 

Second,  The  definitions  must  be  given  in  such  a  way 
that  they  express  definite  measurable  quantities ;  and  in 
order  to  verify  and  apply  the  formula,  methods  must  be 
devised  for  measuring  these  quantities  as  they  occur  in 
nature,  and  these  measurements  must  be  actually  carried 
out.2 


13. 

Lines  of 
thought 
emanating 
from  it. 


1  It  will  be  readily  admitted  that 
the  definition  of  force  as  measured 
by  change  of  motion,  and  the  defi- 
nition of  mass  as  the  quantity  of 
matter,  are  definitions  involving 
some  difficulty.  As  to  distance, 
it  may  be  thought  that  this  is  a 
purely  mathematical,  not  a  physi- 
cal quantity.  So  it  would  be  if 
physical  bodies  were  mathematical 
points,  such  as  the  planets  in  a 
first  approximation  may  be  con- 
sidered to  be.  But  in  comparing 
the  attraction  of  the  earth  upon 
a  body  at  its  surface  with  that  on 
the  moon,  the  dimensions  of  the 
earth  could  not  be  neglected,  and 
the  problem  presented  itself  how 
the  quantities  of  mass  and  distance, 
in  the  case  of  the  earth  and  the 
body  on  its  surface,  had  to  be  de- 
fined. It  appears  from  a  statement 
by  Prof.  Glaisher  (see  Rouse  Ball, 
'  History  of  Mathematics,'  p.  297, 
&c.)  that  the  publication  of  the 
'  Principia,'  containing  the  gravita- 
tion formula,  was  delayed,  because 
Newton  found  it  difficult  to  prove 
that  in  a  sphere  the  different  parts 

VOL.  I. 


with  their  different  distances  from 
any  point  need  not  be  considered 
separately,  but  that  a  quantity 
equal  to  the  whole  mass  situated 
at  the  centre  of  the  sphere  may 
be  substituted.  Laplace  showed  a 
century  later  that  this  property  of 
the  sphere  exists  only  for  one  de- 
creasing function  of  the  distance — 
viz.,  that  of  the  inverse  duplicate 
ratio.  It  exists  likewise  for  that 
function  which  increases  in  propor- 
tion to  the  distance,  but  for  none 
other  (see  '  Principia,'  1st  ed.,  pp. 
198,  200  ;  'Me"canique  celeste,'  1st 
ed.,  vol.  i.  p.  143).  Hitherto  the 
delay  in  publishing  the  '  Principia ' 
was  (see  Brewster,  'Life  of  New- 
ton,' vol.  i.  p.  290)  always  attrib- 
uted to  the  erroneous  figure  of  the 
moon's  distance  from  the  earth, 
with  which  Newton  had  been 
reckoning,  and  which  did  not  sat- 
isfy the  gravitation  formula. 

^  Up  to  the  beginning  of  this 
century  the  merit  of  carrying  out 
accurate  measurements  of  astrono- 
mical constants  is  about  equally 
divided  between  France  and  Eng- 


322 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


Third,  the  formula  is  a  mathematical  expression,  and,  as 
such,  can  be  subjected  to  purely  mathematical  analysis : 
this  analysis  may  refer  to  purely  algebraical  processes  of 


land  ;  the  former  country  having 
supplied  the  means  and  organised 
many  expeditions  (under  Kicher, 
Picard,  Cassini,  La  Condamine, 
Maupertuis,  and  others),  the  latter 
having  invented  and  furnished  the 
greater  portion  of  the  delicate  in- 
struments, through  Newton,  Greg- 
ory, Ramsden,  Dollond,  Harrison, 
and  others.  The  latter  was  a 
matter  of  personal,  the  former  one 
of  organised,  talent.  England  did 
not  take  any  great  part  in  the  re- 
peated measurements  of  the  arc  of 
the  meridian  till,  towards  the  end 
of  the  eighteenth  century  (1785-87), 
the  French  astronomer  Cassini  de 
Thury  presented  to  the  Royal  So- 
ciety a  memorial  on  the  uncertainty 
in  the  difference  of  longitude  of 
Greenwich  and  Paris,  and  proposed 
that  the  English  and  French  mathe- 
maticians in  concert  should  deter- 
mine, by  geodetic  operations,  the 
distance  measured  along  an  arc  of 
parallel.  This  was  assented  to,  and 
the  late  Astronomer  Royal  (G.  B. 
Airy)  claims  that  it  "may  be  said 
that  in  this  as  in  other  grand  ex- 
periments, though  we  began  later 
than  our  Continental  neighbours, 
we  conducted  our  operations  with 
a  degree  of  accuracy  of  which,  till 
that  time,  no  one  had  dared  to 
form  an  idea."  Since  the  begin- 
ning of  this  century  Germany  has, 
through  the  accurate  measurements 
of  Gauss  and  Bessel,  and  through 
the  famous  establishments  of  Fraun- 
hofer,  Steinheil,  Repsold,  and  others, 
taken  a  leading  position  both  in  the 
theory  and  practice  of  measuring. 
So  far  as  gravitational  astronomy 
is  concerned,  the  United  States  of 
America  seem  at  the  end  of  this 
century  to  eclipse  all  previous 
performances.  But  if  we  owe  to 


English    genius    the    invention    of 
logarithms,  the  sextant,  the  reflect- 
ing and  the  achromatic  telescope, 
the    theodolite,    and    the    chrono- 
meter, we  owe  to  France  the  idea 
of  an  absolute  system  of  measure- 
ments   and    the    first    approxima- 
tion to  it  in  the  metrical  system, 
which  England  has  been  tardy  to 
adopt.     A  really  absolute  unit  of 
measurement,  as  the  ten-millionth 
part  of  the  earth  quadrant  was  in- 
tended to  be — one  which  would  be 
recoverable,   if  every   actually   ex- 
isting pattern  was  destroyed — does 
not    yet    indeed    exist ;    but    the 
Government  of  the  Revolution  laid 
the    foundation    in    1790    of    our 
present  international  decimal  cen- 
tigrade system.      It  does  not   ap- 
pear that  the  idea  of  extending  this 
system    to    all    other    forces    and 
quantities  in  nature  was  then  con- 
templated.     A  valuable   contribu- 
tion towards  this  desirable  object 
was  made  by  Fourier,  who  in  his 
celebrated  'Theorie  de  la  Chaleur' 
(1822,   p.  152,  &c.)  laid  down  the 
doctrine   of   the    "dimensions"   of 
physical   quantities   which   had   to 
be   measured   and   compared   with 
each  other.     The  first  who  reduced 
the    measurement    of    other    than 
purely   mechanical    phenomena    to 
the  standard  of  mechanical  forces 
was  Gauss  (1832).     In  his  investi- 
gations  referring  to  the  intensity 
of  magnetic  force  at  different  points 
of  the  earth,  he  found  it  necessary 
to  abandon  the  unit  of  weight,  the 
gramme,  and  to  adopt  the  unit  of 
mass,   inasmuch  as   the  weight  of 
the  unit  of  mass  varied  at  different 
points  of  the  globe.     He  introduced 
the    name   "absolute"   to    signify 
that  this  standard  is  independent 
of  local  or  relative  influences  (see 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF   NATURE.        323 


calculation,  or  to  geometrical  figures.  These  geometrical 
figures  represent  on  paper,  and  on  a  small  scale,  the 
curves  or  orbits  of  bodies  in  space  and  time,  and  can 
be  interpreted  as  such.  Then,  as  in  nature  two  bodies 
or  portions  of  matter  are  never  single  gravitating  points 
occurring  alone,  but  are  surrounded  by  the  totality  of 
existing  things,  the  formula  which  reduces  the  action  of 
gravitation  to  that  of  pairs  of  things,  and  to  the  elements 
of  matter,  requires  to  be  extended  to  more  than  two — in 
fact  to  an  infinity  of  elements.  The  infinitesimal  calculus 
teaches  us  how  to  deal  with  such  a  progression  from  finite 
numbers  and  quantities  to  infinite  numbers  ;  or  from  rela- 
tions which  refer  to  infinitesimal  elements  to  finite  meas- 
urable quantities.  We  find  very  soon  that  our  powers  of 
calculation  reach  only  a  small  way,  and  cover  only  a  small 
extent  of  the  ground  which  observation  opens  to  our  eyes. 
We  are  thus  forced  to  deal  with  the  element  of  error  u. 

.  .        Element  of 

which  creeps  into  our  calculations ;  to  be  satisfied  with  error, 
approximations  ; l  and  instead  of  certainty,  probability  is 


<Jauss,  Werke,  vol.  v.  pp.  85,  293, 
&c.)  Of  Weber's  electrodynainic 
measurements  I  shall  speak  later  on. 
Absolute  measurements  were  used 
by  William  Thomson  (Lord  Kelvin) 
as  early  as  1851,  and  owing  mainly 
to  his  influence  the  present  system 
was  gradually  established  in  the 
course  of  the  following  twenty  years 
(see  William  Thomson,  '  Popular 
Lectures  and  Addresses,'  vol.  i.  p. 
83,  &c.)  Fourier's  theory  of  dimen- 
sions was  first  brought  prominently 
before  the  scientific  and  teaching 
world  by  Clerk  Maxwell  in  his  trea- 
tise on  '  Electricity  and  Magnetism  ' 
(1st  ed.,  vol.  i.  p.  2).  There  also 
we  meet  for  the  first  time  with 
the  use  of  astronomical  magnitudes 
•and  relations  by  which  the  usual 


three  units,  time,  mass,  and  dis- 
tance, can  be  reduced  to  two.  This 
is  also  lucidly  explained  by  Lord 
Kelvin  (loc.  cit.)  It  has  been  fol- 
lowed up  in  detail  in  two  interest- 
ing papers  by  W.  Winter  in  Exner's 
'  Repertorium  der  Physik '  (vol.  21, 
p.  775,  and  vol.  24,  p.  471). 

1  The  history  of  astronomical  cal- 
culations since  the  time  of  Newton, 
when  the  theoretical  basis  was  once 
for  all  laid,  is  a  history  of  gradual 
approximations.  Mathematically  a 
conic  section  is  sufficiently  defined 
if  the  position  of  the  focus  (the  sun 
in  our  planetary  system)  and  three 
positions  of  the  moving  star  are 
known  by  observation.  But  it  was 
a  long  time  before  even  tolerably 
complete  methods  of  observation 


324 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


the  best  we  can  attain  to  in  our  results.1  An  entirely 
new  branch  of  investigation  springs  up — viz.,  the  theory 
of  error,  the  doctrine  of  probability,  and  the  investigation 


and  calculation  were  invented  to 
deal  practically  with  the  problem. 
Up  to  1781,  when  the  new  planet 
Uranus  was  discovered  by  Her- 
schel,  the  interest  centred  mainly 
in  the  determination  of  the  orbits 
of  comets,  which  were  assumed  to 
be  parabolic.  Halley  was  the  first 
to  calculate  these  by  means  of  ten- 
tative methods  given  by  Xewton  in 
the  '  Principia.'  After  1781  the  ne- 
cessity arose  of  determining  closed 
orbits,  and  a  first  attempt  was  made 
to  do  so  by  assuming  circular  orbits 
(neglecting  the  ellipticity)  and  ne- 
glecting the  inclination  of  the  plane 
of  the  orbit  to  that  of  the  earth. 
But  in  the  first  year  of  this  century 
neither  the  parabolic  nor  the  circular 
figure  of  the  orbits  seemed  to  an- 
swer in  the  case  of  the  new  planet 
Ceres,  nor  could  the  inclination"  of 
the  orbit  be  neglected.  It  required 
all  the  skill  of  Gauss  to  tackle  the 
entire,  unabbreviated  problem,  and 
this  was  done  in  his  fundamental 
work  '  Theoria  motus  corporum 
ccelestium.'  As  the  'Principia' 
form  the  foundation  of  all  physical, 
so  does  the  '  Theoria  motus '  of  all 
calculating  astronomy.  A  similar 
fundamental  work  which  should  take 
the  next  important  step,  solving 
generally  the  problem  of  the  motion 
of  a  body  which  is  attracted  from 
more  than  one  fixed  or  movable 
centre  (the  problem  of  three  bodies), 
would  mark  the  next  great  era  in 
calculating  astronomy.  Hitherto 
this  problem  has  only  been  treated 
under  the  assumption  that  the  third 
attracting  body  disturbs  the  real 
orbit  which  has  been  calculated. 
The  necessity  of  solving  the  prob- 
lem of  three  bodies  has  made  itself 
felt  in  the  theory  of  the  moon  and 
other  satellites,  which  stand  under 


the  influence  of  the  main  planet  as 
well  as  the  sun,  and  where  therefore 
the  ellipsis  of  Kepler  cannot  even 
be  taken  as  a  first  approximation. 
And  here  again  the  necessity  of  tak- 
ing into  account  the  volume  and 
the  figures  of  the  attracting  bodies 
still  further  complicates  the  prob- 
lem. On  them  depend  the  preces- 
sion of  the  equinoxes  and  the  ir- 
regularity of  the  precession  known 
under  the  name  of  nutation. 

1  According  to  Wolf  ('  Handbuch 
der  Astronomic,'  vol.  i.  p.  128  sqq.) 
the  merit  of  having  first  considered 
the  best  methods  of  dealing  with 
errors  of  observation  belongs  to 
Picard  (1670)  and  Roger  Cotes 
('  Aestimatio  errorum  in  mixta 
mathesi,'  1722).  The  former  seems 
to  have  first  used  the  apparently  so 
obvious  rule  of  taking  the  arith- 
metical mean  of  a  number  of  ob- 
servations, the  latter  introduced 
the  notion  of  attributing  to  each 
observation  its  value  or  weight. 
Cotes  accordingly  found  that  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  a  number  of 
weighted  points  distributed  over  a 
plane  coincided  with  the  position  of 
greatest  probability.  Gauss  sus- 
pected that  Tobias  Mayer  had 
already  employed  modern  methods 
in  his  calculation  of  long  series  of 
observations,  and  he  himself  used 
what  is  termed  after  Legendre  the 
"  method  of  least  squares  "  as  early 
as  1795.  It  was  not  published  till 
1806  by  Legendre,  in  his  memoir 
'  Xouvelles  methodes  pour  la  deter- 
mination des  orbites  des  cometes. ' 
Gauss  published  his  methods  in  1809 
in  the  celebrated  'Theoria  motus 
corporum  ccelestium.'  This  method 
of  finding  the  most  probable  result 
when  a  larger  number  of  equations 
is  given  than  unknown  quantities 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW   OF   NATURE.        325 


of  the  degree  of  approximation  which  we  can  attain  to. 
And  this  does  not  only  refer  to  the  methods  of  calculation 
which  we  adopt, — is  not  only  a  consequence  of  the  limits 
of  our  mathematical  powers;  this  element  of  error  attaches 
likewise  to  our  actual  observations,  to  the  imperfection  of 
our  senses  and  of  our  instruments.  The  many  sources 
of  mistake  and  inaccuracy  which  surround  us  may  either 
combine  to  produce  an  absolutely  useless  result,  or  may 
be  adroitly  adjusted  so  as  very  largely  to  destroy  each 
other.1  The  arrangement  of  instruments  of  observation 
and  calculation,  so  as  to  minimise  our  errors,  is  a  special 
branch  of  science.  Before  the  time  of  Newton  few  minds 


is  the  same  as  that  of  finding  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  a  number  of 
weighted  points.  This  centre  has 
the  property  that  the  sum  of  the 
squares  of  its  distances  from  these 
points  is  a  minimum.  After  the 
method  had  been  introduced,  La- 
place and  Gauss  independently  tried 
to  prove  it  by  a  variety  of  considera- 
tions. These  have  not  always  been 
accepted  as  conclusive,  though  it  is 
remarkable  that  very  different  ways 
of  attacking  the  problem  all  lead  to 
the  same  result,  and  that  the  rule 
is  confirmed  by  actual  trials  on  a 
large  scale.  It  has  been  shown  that 
the  method  of  least  squares  in  the 
case  of  a  series  of  observations  of 
one  and  the  same  quantity  is  equal 
to  taking  the  arithmetical  mean, — a 
process  which  recommends  itself  to 
common-sense,  though  it  is  not  easy 
to  prove  it  mathematically  to  be  the 
best.  On  the  whole,  the  calculus 
of  probabilities  and  the  so-called 
law  of  error  are  attempts  to  put 
into  figures  and  mathematical  for- 
mulae a  few  common-sense  notions, 
and  it  is  interesting  to  see  to  what 
complicated  processes  of  reasoning 
a  combination  of  these  simple  no- 
tions may  lead.  The  literature  of 


the  subject,  belonging  almost  en- 
tirely to  this  century,  is  very  large, 
Laplace  and  Gauss  heading  the  list. 
Encke  has  summarised  the  scattered 
discussions  of  Gauss  and  Bessel  in 
his  memoir  on  the  subject,  reprinted 
in  Taylor's  '  Scientific  Memoirs '  and 
in  the  2nd  vol.  of  Encke's  '  Abhand- 
lungen,'  Berlin,  1888.  De  Morgan, 
Airy,  and  Jevons  ('  Principles  of 
Science,'  vol.  i.)  in  England  have 
done  much  to  popularise  the  sub- 
ject, and  Bertrand  ('  Calcul  des  Pro- 
babilites,'  1888)  has  very  fully  dis- 
cussed the  principles  of  the  whole 
matter  and  shown  up  the  weak 
points.  The  application  of  the  cal- 
culus to  statistics  will  occupy  us  in 
a  future  chapter. 

1  Not  only  has  every  instrument 
its  constant  errors,  but  even  every 
observer  himself  has  what  is  called 
a  personal  equation — i.  e.,  he  is  sub- 
ject to  constant  errors  of  observa- 
tion, dependent  on  the  peculiarity 
of  his  sense  organs,  or  his  tem- 
perament, &c.  This  was  hardly 
recognised  at  the  beginning  of  this 
century,  when  Maskelyue,  the  As- 
tronomer Royal,  dismissed  an  as- 
sistant whose  observations  showed 
a  constant  difference  from  his  own. 


326  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

were  occupied  with  the  many  researches  indicated  here. 
But  as  the  contents  of  the  '  Principia '  became  familiar 
and  intelligible  to  men  of  science,  a  large  army  of 
workers,  collected  from  all  sides,  had  within  the  first 
century  after  its  publication  accumulated  a  great  mass  of 
is.  research.  It  is  the  glory  of  the  old  French  Academy  of 

Laplace  and    _,    . 

Newton.  Sciences,  in  spite  of  the  opposition  to  .Newton  that  ruled 
there  for  some  time,  to  have  in  all  earnest  taken  up  his 
great  bequest,  and  to  have  made  such  a  summary  possible 
as  was  given  by  Laplace  in  the  two  works  above  re- 
ferred to.  To  Laplace  belongs  also  almost  exclusively  the 
merit  of  having  recognised  the  importance  which  attaches 
in  all  human  science  to  the  existence  of  error,  and  of 
having  founded  the  theory  of  probability.  The  element 
of  error  cannot  be  eliminated  from  our  observations  and 
our  reasonings  :  the  only  true  scientific  method  is  to 
measure  and  study  it. 

The  gravitation  formula  of  Newton  not  only  brought 
precision  and  definiteness  into  scientific  work  in  the  three 
directions  mentioned  above — it  not  only  produced  strict 
definitions  of  the  fundamental  notions  of  dynamics,  pro- 
moted accurate  measurements  of  physical  quantities,  and 
inaugurated  a  new  literature  in  pure  mathematics  ;  but  it 
had,  as  all  other  great  generalisations  have  had  since,  a 
very  far-reaching  influence  on  scientific  thought  in  other 
16.  ways.  There  always  have  been,  and  always  will  be, 

Several  .  . 

interests      several   distinct   interests  which   induce   men   to   study 

which  J 

ISce*  nature.  Some  are  driven  to  it  by  curiosity,  or  a  pure 
love  of  nature.  To  those  who  belong  to  this  class  the 
end  of  the  study  of  nature  is  to  describe  and  to  portray 
the  objects  which  surround  us,  to  see  and  know  them 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATUEE.        327 

better.  It  would  seem  as  if  to  such  minds  the  scientific 
formula,  the  so-called  law  of  nature,  must  be  distasteful, 
and  probably  useless.  Nevertheless  the  scientific  view,  of 
which  the  mathematical  formula  is  an  extreme  expres- 
sion, has  reacted,  though  not  always  beneficially,  upon 
the  labours  of  those  who  confine  themselves  to  observa- 
tion and  description ;  it  has  given  to  their  efforts  general 
interest  and  encouragement,  indicated  new  directions,  and 
frequently  opened  new  fields.  Thus  the  new  formula  of 
Copernicus  and  Galileo  gave  a  great  impetus  to  star- 
gazing, which  was  greatly  increased  by  the  almost  con- 
temporary invention  of  the  telescope.  The  new  theory 
required  the  rotation  of  the  planets,  and  led  to  minute 
observations  of  their  phases,  and  to  the  discovery  of  the 
satellites  of  Jupiter  and  the  ring  of  Saturn.  Variable 
stars  were  incidentally  discovered  by  Tycho,  and  the 
long- neglected  comets  received  greater  attention.  Ber- 
noulli attempted,  and  Halley  actually  carried  out,  the 
calculation  of  the  return  of  a  comet.  Still  later — in 
fact,  not  before  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  or  the  beginning 
of  the  present  century — came  the  turn  for  reliable  obser- 
vation of  meteors  and  auroras ;  for  as  late  as  1790  the 
'  Decade  philosophique,'  as  well  as  the  Paris  Academy  and 
many  learned  persons,  ridiculed  the  authentic  reports  of 
the  fall  of  meteors,  and  Chladni's  classical  dissertation  on 
the  stone  of  Pallas.1  It  seems  as  if  the  purest  love  of 

1  When   in   the    year    1790   the      better  to  deny  such  incredible  things 


municipality  of  Juillac  in  Gascony 
submitted  a  report,  signed  by  more 
than  300  eyewitnesses,  to  the  Paris 
Academy,  on  a  fall  of  stones  which 
had  there  taken  place,  one  of  the 


than  to  enter  into  any  explanations. 
Bertholon  could  not  help  pitying  a 
community  which  had  such  a  foolish 
maire,  and  remarked  in  the  '  Jour- 
nal des  Sciences  utiles ' :  "  How  sad 


editors    of    the    '  Decade    philoso-    |   it  is  to  find  a  whole  municipality 
phique '  remarked  that  it  would  be   j   attesting  formally  by  protocol  popu- 


328  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

17.       nature,  the  greatest  devotion  of  the  observer  and  the 

Insuffici- 
ency of  mere  collector,  lead  only  a  little  way  in  finding  out  the  hidden 

observation. 

paths  of  natural  things  or  the  behaviour  of  natural  ob- 
jects ;  and  however  grateful  we  must  be  to  those  pioneers 
of  knowledge  who  with  unrewarded  patience  amass  the 
material  for  later  theorists,  it  is  to  the  classification  of  a 
Linnaeus,  to  the  arrangements  of  a  Cuvier,  to  the  theories 
of  a  Darwin,  to  the  measurements  of  a  Bradley  and  a 
Herschel,  most  of  all  to  the  formulae  of  a  Xewton  or  a 
Gauss,  followed  by  the  calculations  of  their  pupils,  that 
we  are  indebted  for  a  real  grasp,  for  a  comprehensive 
knowledge,  of  great  masses  of  natural  phenomena. 
IB.  Next  to  the  pure  love  of  nature,  the  desire  to  apply 

interest.  natural  knowledge,  and  to  make  it  useful  for  practical 
purposes,  has  rendered  in  return  great  services  to  science. 
The  Royal  Society  and  the  Royal  Institution  had  both 
from  their  infancy  a  large  admixture  of  the  practical 
spirit.  These  were  founded,  more  even  than  the  academies 
abroad,  to  a  great  extent  upon  the  desire  to  make  know- 
ledge useful. 

The  Governments  of  England  and  of  France  promoted 

lar  fables  which  are  only  to  be  pitied!  origin.  Fortunately,  a  remarkable 
What  can  I  add  to  such  a  protocol  I  fall  of  stones,  accompanied  by 
The  philosophical  reader  will  him-  meteoric  phenomena,  took  place  in 
self  suggest  what  to  say  when  he  1803  not  far  from  Paris,  at  1'Aigie 
reads  this  authentic  proof  of  an  in  the  department  de  1'Orne,  and 
evidently  wrong  fact,  of  a  pheno-  Biot  was  commissioned  by  the 
menon  which  is  physically  impos-  Academy  to  proceed  to  the  dis- 
able" (Wolf, 'Geschichteder  Astro-  trict  and  examine  the  case.  In  the 
nomie,'  1877,  p.  697  tq.)  Chladni  '  Relation,'  ic..  which  he  read  before 
published  his  essay  on  the  large  the  Institute,  he  established  the 
mass  of  iron  found  by  the  traveller  fact  that  a  meteor  exploded  in  the 
Pallas  in  Siberia  in  the  year  1794,  district,  and  that  at  the  same  time 
and,  in  spite  of  adverse  criticisms,  ,  a  fall  of  many  thousand  stones, 
followed  it  up  by  a  catalogue  and  ,  weighing  about  20  tons,  took  place 


an  atlas  of   meteoric   stones,  sug- 
gesting that  they  were  of  cosmic 


(Biot.    '  Melanges    scientifiques    et 
litteraires,'  voL  L  p.  15  tqq.) 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW   OF    NATURE.        329 

the  study  of  the  "  mechanics  of  the  heavens  "  by  offering 
large  prizes  for  scientific  and  practical  means  of  deter- 
mining the  longitude  at  sea.  The  lunar  theory,  which 
has  occupied  the  attention  of  the  greatest  mathematicians 
since  Newton — of  Euler,  Clairaut,  and  Tobias  Mayer  in 
the  last  century ;  of  Burckhardt,  Plana,  and  Hansen,  of 
Delaunay  and  Adams,  in  the  present  century — was  an 
outcome  of  this.  It  still  engages  the  attention  of  scien- 
tific minds,  involving  as  it  does  all  the  most  delicate 
astronomical  calculations,  whilst  for  practical  nautical 
purposes  the  moon  has  ceased  to  be  the  great  timekeeper, 
and  has  since  1763  been  replaced  by  the  wonderful 
chronometers  of  Harrison  and  his  successors.  A  similar 
stimulus  both  to  abstract  scientific  research  and  to  the 
perfection  of  the  practical  instruments  of  measurement 
was  given  in  this  century  by  the  development  of  sub- 
marine telegraphy  :  in  this  case  both  sides  of  the  problem, 
the  scientific  and  the  practical,  were  attacked,  and  carried 
to  a  high  degree  of  perfection  by  one  and  the  same  mind1 — 

1  William  Thomson's  (Lord  Kel-  j  the  signals  and  the  gradual  increase 

vin's)  investigations  and  inventions,  j  of  the  strength  of  the  electric  cur- 

which  made  submarine  telegraphy  |  rent  at  the  receiving  end  of  long 

at  long  distances  commercially  prac-  submarine  cables  ("  On  the  Theory 

ticable,  refer  mainly  to  the  over-  I  of    the    Electric    Telegraph "    and 

coming   of   the    "embarrassment"  other  papers,  reprinted  in  the  2nd 

occasioned   by   the    property   (dis-  j  vol.  of  'Math,  and  Phys.  Papers,' 


covered  by  Werner  Siemens,  1849, 


which    submerged    cables    possess 


1884).      The    importance   of    con- 


and  investigated  by  Faraday,  1854)       structing  delicate  instruments  for 


registering  feeble    signals,   and   of 


of  "retaining  a  quantity  of  elec-  j  a  method  for  reducing  the  time 
tricity  in  charge  along  the  whole  j  of  single  signals,  became  evident 
surface."  In  1854  Thomson  made  through  these  theoretical  invest! - 


a  full  theoretical  examination  of 
this  phenomenon,  showed  how  it 
depended  on  the  length,  the  elec- 


gations.  The  mirror  galvanometer 
was  first  used  in  1858  on  the  first 
Atlantic  cable,  and  afterwards  on 


trie    resistance,    and    the    electro-  the  successful  cables  of  1865  and 

static  capacity  of  the  line,  and  gave  1866.       It    was    followed    by    the 

a  mathematical  formula,  with  prac-  ;    spark  -  recorder,   which   led   to   the 

tical  examples  of  the  retardation  of  i   syphon -recorder   (1867-70),  which 


330 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


an  almost  unique  instance  of  the  combination  of  abstract 
reasoning  and  practical  inventiveness.  An  almost  equally 
important  problem,  having  both  scientific  and  practical 
interest,  arising  out  of  the  Xevvtonian  gravitation  formula, 
is  the  problem  of  the  tides.  Here  also  the  first  suggestions 
towards  a  theory  were  given  in  the  '  Principia/  whereas 
the  first  attempt  at  a  solution  is  contained  in  Laplace's 
great  work.  A  closer  approximation  was  reached  by  Sir 
W.  Thomson  in  his  extensive  theoretical  and  practical  use 
of  Fourier's  mathematics. 

I  shall  have  frequent  opportunity  to  refer  to  the  bene- 
ficial and  fructifying  influence  which  practical  problems 
have  exerted  on  scientific  thought ; l  in  fact,  in  spite  of 


has  since  been  in  use  in  submarine 
telegraphy.  The  best  account  of 
these  discoveries  and  inventions  is 
to  be  found  in  Lord  Kelvin's  own 
papers,  a  good  summary  being  given 
in  his  short  article  in  Nichol's 
'  Cyclopedia, '  reprinted  as  No.  82, 
vol.  ii.  p.  138. 

1  How  much  science  owes  to  the 
practical  interests  of  navigation  can 
be  seen  by  a  glance  at  the  subjects 
contained  in  the  third  volume  of 
Lord  Kelvin's  '  Popular  Lectures 
and  Addresses.'  The  Tides,  Deep- 
Sea  Sounding,  Cable-Laying,  and 
Terrestrial  Magnetism  all  furnish 
important  practical  as  well  as  high- 
ly abstract  theoretical  problems, 
the  solution  of  which  demands  new 
instruments  and  new  methods  of 
calculation.  The  phenomena  of 
the  tides  and  those  of  terrestrial 
magnetism  are  intimately  connect- 
ed with  two  of  the  most  refined 
mathematical  theories  which  this 
century  has  developed.  The  for- 
mer was  first  attacked  by  the  so- 
called  equilibrium  theory — the  pro- 
blem being  to  find  the  figure  of 
equilibrium  of  a  rotating  ellipsoid 


covered  with  water  under  the  in- 
fluence of  various  attracting  forces. 
Laplace,  followed  by  Airy  and 
Thomson,  showed  how  it  is  much 
more  a  question  of  dynamics  than 
of  statics,  and  that  it  resolves  itself 
into  the  analysis  and  subsequent 
synthesis  of  a  number  of  periodic 
movements,  dependent  upon  the 
several  periodic  changes  of  the  ro- 
tation of  the  earth  and  the  revo- 
lutions of  the  moon  round  the 
earth  and  the  sun.  A  general 
method  of  dealing  mathematically 
with  the  superposition  of  several 
periodic  changes  had  been  invented 
by  Fourier  in  the  early  part  of  this 
century,  and  it  was  this  which, 
especially  in  the  hands  of  Lord 
Kelvin  and  his  brother — the  late 
Prof.  James  Thomson — led  to  the 
harmonic  analysis  of  tide  motion 
and  the  subsequent  invention  of 
tide-predicting  apparatus  (see  the 
above  volume,  p.  177  sqq.)  The 
observation  of  the  magnetism  of 
the  earth  is  connected  with  great 
improvements  in  the  theory  and 
construction  of  the  mariner's  com- 
pa*s,  suggested  and  carried  out  by 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATUEE.        331 


the  great  reciprocal  influence  which  science  has  gained  in 
the  course  of  this  century  over  practical  life,  I  am  still 
doubtful  whether  scientific  thought  has,  at  the  end  of 
our  century,  as  yet  balanced  the  debt  which  it  owes  to 
practical  inventors.  It  is  instructive,  for  instance,  to 
consider  how  much,  in  the  hands  of  Bumford,  of  Sadi 
Carnot,  of  Him,  and  of  Bankine,  science  has  learnt  from 
the  steam-engine,  and  to  reflect  whether  from  all  the 
theoretical  insight  gained  any  really  radical  improve- 
ment of  the  steam-engine — still  one  of  the  most  imperfect 
machines — has  resulted.1 


Lord  Kelvin ;  and  it  has  in  an- 
other direction  led  to  remarkable 
scientific  results  in  the  hands  of 
Gauss,  who  between  the  years  1830 
and  1840  brought  the  theory  al- 
most to  perfection.  Here  again 
the  physical  phenomenon  required 
for  its  treatment  a  special  mathe- 
matical analysis,  which  Gauss  great- 
ly furthered  in  his  '  Allgemeine 
Lehrsatze  in  Beziehung  auf  die  im 
verkehrten  Verhaltnisse  des  Quad- 
rats der  Entfernung  wirkenden 
Anziehungs-  und  Abstossungs- 
Krafte '  (1840).  This  is  a  mathema- 
tical investigation  of  the  Newtonian 
gravitation-formula.  Gauss  folio  wed 
out  the  theories  of  Laplace  and  La- 
grange  simultaneously  with  Green, 
whose  now  celebrated  memoir  on 
the  subject  remained  long  unknown 
(see  supra,  pp.  231,  247).  The  ma- 
thematical theory  showed  that  in  a 
sphere  containing  a  certain  amount 
of  attracting  (magnetic)  matter  an 
ideal  distribution  on  the  surface  of 
the  sphere  can  be  found  which 
takes  the  place  of  the  real  but  un- 
known distribution  in  the  interior, 
and  that  if  through  observation  the 
necessary  data  are  supplied,  the 
magnetic  condition  of  any  point 
on  the  surface  can  be  foretold  with 
great  approximation.  As  an  ex- 


ample, Gauss  foretold  from  the 
imperfect  data  at  his  command 
the  position  of  the  south  magnetic 
pole.  In  1840  Capt.  Sir  James  Ross 
approached  it  sufficiently  to  show 
the  correctness  of  the  calculation. 
The  theoretical  investigations  in 
connection  with  magnetic  attrac- 
tion and  with  tidal  movements 
have  remodelled  the  methods  of  ob- 
servation of  the  phenomena  them- 
selves, the  older  methods  having 
proved  to  be  in  many  ways  insuf- 
ficient. A  full  account  of  Gauss's 
labours  here  referred  to  will  be 
found  in  E.  Schering,  '  C.  F.  Gauss 
und  die  Erforschung  des  Erdmag- 
netismus,'  Gb'ttingen,  1887. 

1  I  refer  in  this  matter  to  two 
addresses  delivered  recently  —  one 
by  Prof.  Unwin  ('Electrician,'  vol. 
35,  pp.  50  and  79)  on  "The  De- 
velopment of  the  Experimental 
Study  of  Heat  -  Engines "  ;  the 
other  by  Prof.  Lodge  on  "The 
Second  Law  of  Thermodynamics " 
('Electrician,'  vol.  35,  p.  80  sqq.) 
From  a  perusal  of  these  papers  one 
gains  the  impression  that  science 
has  been  more  successful  in  teach- 
ing us  why  the  steam-engine  is  so 
wasteful  a  machine  than  in  show- 
ing how  it  can  be  greatly  improved. 
It  is  interesting  to  hear  that  "al- 


332  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

19.  The  mathematical  formula  is  the  point  through  which 

Pocalising 

effect  of       all  the  light  gained  by  science  passes  in  order  to  be  of 

mathemati-  » 

cai  formula.  USQ  t0  practice ;  it  is  also  the  point  in  which  all  know- 
ledge gained  by  practice,  experiment,  and  observation  must 
be  concentrated  before  it  can  be  scientifically  grasped. 
The  more  distinct  and  marked  the  point,  the  more  con- 
centrated will  be  the  light  coming  from  it,  the  more  un- 
mistakable the  insight  conveyed.  All  scientific  thought, 
from  the  simple  gravitation  formula  of  Newton,  through 
the  more  complicated  formulae  of  physics  and  of  chem- 
istry, the  vaguer  so-called  laws  of  organic  and  animated 
nature,  down  to  the  uncertain  statements  of  psychology 
and  the  data  of  our  social  and  historical  knowledge,  alike 
partakes  of  this  characteristic,  that  it  is  an  attempt  to 
gather  up  the  scattered  rays  of  light,  the  diffused  know- 
ledge, in  a  focus,  from  whence  it  can  be  again  spread  out 
and  analysed,  according  to  the  abstract  processes  of  the 
thinking  mind.  But  only  where  this  can  be  done  with 
mathematical  precision  and  accuracy  is  the  image  sharp 
and  well  defined,  and  the  deductions  clear  and  unmis- 
takable. As  we  descend  from  the  mechanical,  through 
the  physical,  chemical,  and  biological,  to  the  mental, 
moral,  and  social  sciences,  the  process  of  focalisation 
becomes  less  and  less  perfect, — the  sharp  point,  the 


most  all  the  present  difference  be- 
tween the  best  steam-engine  and 
the  worst  is  some  5  or  6  per  cent " 
(Lodge).  Prof.  Unwin  sums  up  by 


provement  of  the  steam-engine  to 
the  exclusion  of  either  of  the 
others.  .  .  .  Representing  perhaps 
rather  the  scientific  than  the  prac- 


saying :  "Since  1845  purely  scien-  j  tical  interest,  I  do  not  think  that 
tific  men,  scientific  experimenters,  j  the  mathematical  and  physical  re- 
and  practical  engineers  have  all  searches  of  which  I  have  tried  to 
been  engaged  in  the  study  of  the  :  give  an  account  have  had  no  in- 
steam -engine.  I  do  not  believe  ;  flueuce  on  the  practical  business  of 
that  any  one  of  the  three  can  j  the  engineer." 
claim  all  the  credit  for  the  im-  i 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW   OF    NATURE.        333 


focus,  is  replaced  by  a  larger  or  a  smaller  circle,  the 
contours  of  the  image  become  less  and  less  distinct, 
and  with  the  possible  light  which  we  gain  there  is 
mingled  much  darkness,  the  source  of  many  mistakes 
and  errors.  But  the  tendency  of  all  scientific  thought 
is  towards  clearer  and  clearer  definition ;  it  lies  in  the 
direction  of  a  more  and  more  extensive  use  of  mathe- 
matical measurements,  of  mathematical  formulae. 

There  is  probably  no  science  which  has  come  so  per- 
fectly under  the  control  of  this  kind  of  mathematical  ex- 
pression as  has  astronomy  since  the  time  of  Newton  or  of 
Laplace,  and,  we  may  add,  there  exists  probably  no  mathe- 
matical formula  which  has  stood  the  test  of  application  to 
existing  phenomena  so  long  and  so  thoroughly  as  the 
gravitation  formula  of  Newton.  It  possesses  two  unique 
properties  which  no  other  formula  possesses — so  far  as  we 
can  now  see — it  is  universal l  and  it  is  accurate.2  These 


1  The  law  of  gravitation  can  be 
called  the  first  and  most  general 
physical  law  or  statement  of  uni- 
versal application.  The  laws  of 
motion  may  be  called  mechanical 
or  dynamical  statements.  Both 
the  law  of  gravitation  and  the 
laws  of  motion  describe  facts,  and 
have  been  found  by  experience  ; 
but  the  laws  of  motion  con- 
tain no  physical  constant — i.e., 
no  quantity  which  requires  to  be 
fixed  and  measured  by  observa- 
tion, and  the  absolute  value  of 
which  has  for  us  at  present  no 
ulterior  meaning.  The  law  of  gra- 
vitation has  one  physical  constant, 
the  universal  gravitation  constant 
(see  p.  320).  As  it  measures  what 
we  call  matter,  it  need  not  be  de- 
termined, and  its  actual  determin- 
ation, which  has  been  accurately 
made  only  in  recent  times,  has  not 


in  any  direction  advanced  our  gen- 
eral physical  knowledge.  For  all 
practical  purposes  of  physics  the 
unit  of  mass  is  a  weight,  just  as  for 
all  commercial  purposes  gold  is  the 
standard  of  value.  The  astrono- 
mical view  permits  us  to  go  a  step 
further  and  express  the  mass  of  a 
pound  of  matter  in  units  of  time 
and  space,  and  the  political  econo- 
mist may  seek  for  a  real  standard 
of  value — for  instance,  an  article 
of  food  like  wheat.  Other  funda- 
mental physical  laws  or  general 
statements  involve  other  physical 
constants,  as  we  shall  see  later  on. 
2  The  accuracy  of  the  so-called 
laws  of  nature,  or,  more  correctly, 
of  the  expressions  which  science 
gives  to  the  laws  of  nature,  is  a 
very  important  question.  Little  is 
said  on  this  point  in  the  ordinary 
text  -  books.  It  is  only  in  very 


334 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


two  properties  of  the  gravitation  formula  have  been  brought 
out  by  a  long  line  of  investigations,  carried  on  with  the 
view  of  substantiating  or  of  refuting  the  formula.  They 
mark  the  development  of  whole  sciences,  the  foundation 
of  quite  novel  branches  of  research.  I  propose  briefly  to 
follow  up  these  developments. 
20.  Common-sense  has  never  had  any  difficultv  in  knowing 

Matter  and 

<orce  mathe-  what  matter  and  force  are,  or  in  defining  them  for  the 
-defined,       purposes  of  practical  life.     But  it  took  thousands  of  years 
.to  find  a  definition  of  these  quantities  which  could  serve 
.as  the  basis  of  exact  measurement,  and  permit  calcula- 
tions of  results  into  which  both  factors  entered  in  varying 


recent  publications  that  attention 
is  sufficiently  drawn  to  the  fact 
that  very  few  mathematical  for-  i 
mulae  in  physics  or  chemistry  are  , 
-more  than  approximations.  The 
law  of  gravitation  is  one  of  the  few 
mathematical  expressions  which,  ! 
besides  being  universal,  have  stood 
the  most  rigorous  tests  as  to  accur- 
acy. A  most  interesting  attempt 
to  prove  the  inaccuracy  of  New- 
ton's law  was  made,  but  speedily 
abandoned,  by  Clairaut,  one  of 
the  earliest  Newtonians  in  the  old 
Academy  of  Sciences.  Clairaut 
began  about  1743  to  study  the 
lunar  theory  in  the  light  of  New- 
ton's system,1  which  Madrin  be- 
fore him  had  already  despaired 
of  reconciling  with  the  facts  of 
observation.  When  he  himself, 
on  calculating  the  animal  motion 
of  the  moon's  apogee  (or  farthest 
point  in  its  orbit  round  the 
earth),  found  only  half  the  value 
which  observation  furnished,  he  was 
tempted  in  his  communication  to 
the  Academy  of  November  1747  to 
suggest  that  the  Newtonian  for- 
mula might  require  a  correction  for 
great  distances.  This  suggestion 
was  followed,  as  Lalande  tells  us, 


by  a  veritable  scandal  in  the  learned 
world.  Buffon,  for  purely  meta- 
physical reasons,  objected  to  this 
infringement  of  the  simplicity  of 
the  laws  of  the  universe.  The 
opponents  of  Newton's  system  had 
a  short  triumph,  which  however 
was  speedily  reversed  when  Clair- 
aut, putting  a  greater  precision 
into  his  calculations  by  taking 
inequalities  into  account  which  he 
had  previously  neglected,  explained 
to  the  Academy  in  ilay  1749  that 
he  had  succeeded  in  reconciling  the 
movement  of  the  moon's  apogee 
with  the  law  of  attraction  accord- 
ing to  the  inverse  square  of  the 
distance.  From  that  time  the 
Newtonian  theory,  to  which  only 
shortly  before  mathematicians  like 
Euler  had  been  won  over,  reigned 
supreme.  See  Lalande  in  the  4th 
volume  of  Montucla's  '  Histoire 
des  Mathematiques,'  p.  67,  &c. 
Euler's  merits  in  solving  many 
problems  in  physical  astronomy  were 
so  great  that  the  Academy  procur- 
ed permission  from  Louis  XV.  to 
receive  him  as  a  tumumeraire,  the 
eight  places  granted  to  external 
members  being  all  occupied. 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        335 

quantities  and  in  varying  combinations.  That  a  smaller 
quantity  of  matter  in  motion  could  produce  the  same 
action  as  a  larger  which  was  moving  slowly,  or  even 
apparently  at  rest,  and  acted  only  by  what  is  termed  its 
dead- weight,  was  a  well-known  phenomenon ;  but  it  was 
only  within  the  half-century  which  preceded  the  publica- 
tion of  the  '  Principia  '  that,  through  the  labours  of  Galileo 
and  of  Huygens,  mathematical  definitions  and  simple 
formulae  were  laid  down,  and  generally  accepted,  which 
gave  the  means  of  accurately  measuring  and  calculating 
the  phenomena  of  moving  bodies  and  the  combination  of 
forces.  These  labours  resulted  in  a  definition  of  matter 
which,  translated  into  the  language  of  our  day,  says  that 
matter  is  that  which  moves  and  is  capable  of  resisting 
any  change  of  motion.  Motion  is  a  measurable  quan- 
tity. For  its  measurement  we  require  the  measurement 
of  space  and  time,  and  the  well-known  relation  of  both 
—viz.,  velocity. 

The  above  formula  therefore  says  that  matter  is  mea- 
sured by  the  resistance  it  offers  to  change  of  motion  or 
of  velocity.  And  correspondingly  force  is  that  which  is 
capable  of  producing  change  of  motion,  or  velocity  in 
matter,  and  it  is  measured  by  the  amount  of  change  it 
produces.  Given  a  definite,  though  unknown,  force, 
portions  of  matter — i.e.,  masses — can  be  compared  by  the 
resistance  they  offer  to  the  change  of  their  motion ;  the 
smaller  the  change  the  larger  the  mass  or  quantity  of 
matter.  Given  a  definite,  though  unknown,  quantity  of 
matter,  forces  can  be  measured  by  the  different  changes 
they  produce  in  the  motion — i.e.,  the  velocity — of  this 
quantity ;  they  are  greater  or  smaller  in  the  proportion 


336  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

of  the  change  of  velocity  which  they  produce.  One  of 
the  great  difficulties  which  stood  in  the  way  of  the  fixing 
of  these  very  simple  mathematical  relations  and  defin- 
itions was  the  fact  that  all  matter  with  which  we  can 
experiment  is  under  the  influence  of  a  constant  but  un- 
known force,  that  which  makes  it  fall  if  not  supported. 
It  was  only  by  freeing  themselves  from  the  effect  of  this 
constant  force,  or  by  balancing  it,  that  philosophers 
gradually  arrived  at  the  conception  and  definition  of 
mass,  or  quantity  of  matter,  as  something  independent 
21.  of  its  weight.  It  was  reserved  for  Newton  to  show  and 
mass.  *  define  the  exact  relation  which  weight  bears  to  the  other 
properties  of  matter  defined  and  measured  by  his  pre- 
decessors. By  doing  so  he  added  a  new  definition,  a  new 
means  of  measuring  the  quantity  of  matter  or  its  mass, 
showing  at  the  same  time  to  what  extent  the  popular 
measure  of  matter — i.e.,  its  weight — could  be  accurately 
used  for  scientific  purposes.  Again,  to  express  it  in  the 
language  of  our  day,  Newton  showed  that  matter  is  not 
only  that  which  offers  resistance  to  change  of  motion, 
but  also  that  which  causes  change  of  motion  in  other 
portions  of  matter :  it  is  not  only  the  object  on  which 
force  spends  itself,  it  is  the  seat  of  this  force,  and  the 
degree  in  which  it  can  change  motion  in  other  portions 
of  matter  is  proportional  to  the  degree  in  which  it 
resists  the  change  of  its  own  motion — in  other  words, 
the  gravity  or  weight  of  matter  is  proportional  to  its  mass 
or  inertia,  and  is  not  dependent  on  any  other  difference, 
whether  of  size  or  of  quality.  This  second  universal 
property  of  matter,  which  brought  out  more  clearly  the 
reciprocity  of  all  mechanical,  and  subsequently  of  all 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        337 

physical  actions,  is,  however,  dependent  on  the  mutual 
distances  of  the  particles  of  matter,  and  can  therefore  be 
altered,  but  can  as  little  as  the  existence  of  matter  itself 
be  removed.  This  view  of  Newton's  explained  or  de- 
scribed clearly l  the  phenomena  of  moving  and  falling 


1  The  distinction  between  an  ex- 
planation and  a  description  of  the 
facts  of  nature  has  been  slowly  de- 
veloped in  the  course  of  modern 
thought.  Probably  Leibniz  was 
the  first  to  insist  on  it,  and  to 
maintain  in  the  abstract  that  all 
description  of  nature  would  be  me- 
chanical, but  that  the  explanation 
or  interpretation  of  nature  must  be 
spiritual.  But  the  first  practical 
instance  of  this  important  distinc- 
tion is  really  to  be  found  in  New- 
ton's philosophy.  In  many  pas- 
sages of  the  '  Principia,'  and  especi- 
ally in  the  '  Optics,'  the  double  view 
of  the  problems  of  philosophy  is 
clearly  indicated.  The  principles 
of  science  since  the  time  of  Newton 
are  general  facts,  established  by 
experience  and  put  into  mathe- 
matical language,  admitting  of  con- 
stant verification  by  observation 
and  by  the  deductions  of  the  cal- 
culus. These  principles  are  not 
the  ultimate  causes,  but  only  a 
concise  description  of  some  of  the 
phenomena  of  nature.  These  prin- 
ciples Newton  calls  mathematical — 
referring  to  measurable  quantities 
— and  distinguishes  them  from  the 
philosophical  principles!  ('Princ.,' 
1st  ed. ,  p.  401).  Especially  as  re- 
gards gravitation,  Newton  explains 
many  times  that  he  uses  this  term 
not  as  an  explanation,  but  only  as 
a  mathematical  description  of.  the 
force  with  which  bodies  approach 
each  other,  whatever  the  cause  of 
this  phenomenon  may  be,  which  he 
leaves  others  (called  with  some 
irony  metaphysicians)  to  deter- 
mine ('Optics,'  query  31).  That 

VOL.  I. 


Newton,  besides  giving  the  precise 
mathematical  principles  of  all  future 
dynamical  science,  indulged  also  in 
further  speculations,  which  he  put 
into  the  form  of  queries  and  ad- 
vanced with  hesitation  and  merely 
tentatively,  gave  his  opponents 
ample  opportunity  to  attack  the 
doubtful  and  uncertain  statements 
in  his  philosophy.  Instead  of 
studying  and  understanding  the 
mathematical  truths  of  the  '  Prin- 
cipia,' they  attacked  the  doctrines 
which  were  fragmentarily  put  for- 
ward in  the  queries  to  the  '  Optics ' 
or  added  in  the  general  scholium 
at  the  end  of  the  second  edition  of 
the  'Principia.'  Roger  Cotes  in 
his  preface  to  the  second  edition 
of  the  'Principia,'  and  Clarke  in 
his  correspondence  with  Leibniz, 
pointed  out  the  difference  between 
Newton's  descriptive  and  calculat- 
ing and  the  older  or  metaphysical 
philosophy.  They  were,  however, 
more  interested  in  disproving  the 
atheistical  consequences  of  which 
Newton's  philosophy  had  been  ac- 
cused than  in  clearly  insisting  on 
the  fundamental  difference  between 
mathematical  and  metaphysical 
principles — i.e.,  between  the  exact 
and  the  philosophical  views  of  na- 
ture. And  in  Bentley's  Boyle  lec- 
tures, delivered  in  1692  and  1693, 
the  principles  of  Newton's  philos- 
ophy were  specially  brought  for- 
ward to  refute  atheism,  an  under- 
taking which  Newton  himself  sup- 
ported in  his  contemporary  corre- 
spondence with  Bentley,  published 
half  a  century  later,  in  1756. 


338 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


22. 

Gravitation 

not  an 


masses,  not  only  at  a  point  on  the  surface  of  our  earth, 
where  the  force  of  gravity  can  be  considered  to  be  con- 
stant, but  all  through  the  universe,  where  it  varies  with 
the  distances  of  the  moving  masses. 

The  Newtonian  formula  of  gravitation  was  not  at  once 
accepted  by  philosophers  as  a  correct  statement  of  the 
of  nature.1     It  appeared  to  limit  the  existence  of 


1  The  philosophy  of  Descartes, 
which  then  reigned  on  the  Con- 
tinent, seemed  in  many  ways  to 
hinder  the  acceptance  of  Newton's 
doctrines.  Descartes  had  taken  a 
great  step  in  advance  in  philosophi- 
cal teaching  ;  he  had  placed  mathe- 
matics at  the  head  of  his  doctrine  ; 
he  had  opposed  the  older  metaphy- 
sical methods,  and  he  had,  through 
his  application  of  algebra  to  geo- 
metry, made  great  progress  towards 
a  mechanical  description  of  phe- 
nomena. But  he  had  not  separated 
the  description  from  the  interpre- 
tation of  nature.  Philosophy  and 
science  remained  united,  the  mathe- 
matical formulae  were  only  a  new 
kind  of  metaphysics,  incapable  with- 
out observation  of  making  any  real 
advance  in  the  knowledge  of  nature. 
The  facts  of  geometry  which  are 
required  for  an  application  of  an- 
alysis are  the  well-known  axioms  of 
Euclid.  An  application  of  analysis 
to  dynamics  requires  a  knowledge 
of  the  laws  or  fundamental  proper- 
ties of  motion.  These  were  not 
correctly  and  completely  known  to 
Descartes  ;  Newton  placed  them  at 
the  head  of  his  mathematical  phil- 
osophy of  nature.  A  further  appli- 
cation to  physical  phenomena  re- 
quired a  knowledge  of  some  general 
physical  fact :  such  was  supplied  by 
Newton  in  the  gravitation  formula. 
The  laws  of  motion  and  gravitation 
once  admitted  as  facts,  there  was 
plenty  to  do  for  mathematics.  Not 
so  with  Descartes.  In  his  philoso- 


|  phy  the  basis  of  facts  was  too  nar- 
row and  indefinite,  and  had  to  be 
supplemented  by  metaphysical  sup- 

I  positions  and  deductions.  The  field 
for  mathematical  reasoning  not  be- 
ing sufficiently  prepared  and  wide 
enough,  Descartes  had  speedily  got 
back  again  into  metaphysical  rea- 
soning. In  fact  the  doctrines  of 
Newton,  in  which  mathematical  and 
philosophical  deductions  had  for  the 
first  time  been  successfully  separ- 
ated, encountered  on  the  Continent 
the  doctrines  of  Descartes,  in  which 
mathematical  and  philosophical  de- 
ductions were  hopelessly  mixed  up. 
On  one  point  especially  the  two 
views  seemed  to  clash.  Descartes 
had  by  metaphysical  considerations 
tried  to  define  what  matter  is. 
Newton  had  postponed  the  answer 
to  this  question,  but  had  defined 
mathematically  two  properties  of 
matter — viz.,  inertia  and  gravita- 
tion. Descartes'  metaphysical  con- 
siderations had  led  to  the  concep- 
tion that  matter  and  extension  were 
identical,  that  space  therefore  could 
not  be  empty.  Newton,  occupying 
himself  not  with  matter  in  the  ab- 
stract, but  only  with  moving  observ- 
able matter,  had  established  the 
general  law  of  gravitation,  leaving 
it  undecided  whether  the  apparent 
vacuum  existing  between  visible 
bodies  was  really  empty  or  full. 
For  the  deductions  from  the  law 
of  gravitation  it  might  in  the 
first  instance  be  considered  empty. 
Thus  on  this  question  about  space 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW    OF   NATURE.        339 


matter  to  certain  changing  places  in  an  empty  space, 
and  to  attach  the  forces  of  nature  likewise  to  this  dis- 
tribution of  matter.  This  was  hardly  the  intention  of 
the  author  himself,  who  saw  in  the  so-called  law  of 
gravitation  not  a  final  explanation,  but  only  a  descrip- 
tion of  the  phenomena  of  nature — notably  of  the  larger 
phenomena.  That  behind  the  mathematical  formula  there 
may  be  conditions  which  are  capable  of  further  analysis, 
— that  the  larger  or  molar  phenomena  of  moving  bodies 
are  made  up  of  their  smaller  or  molecular  movements, 
was  well  known  to  Newton.  For  before  he  approached 
the  great  laws  of  the  universe  he  had  been  occupied 
with  investigations  which  led  him  into  the  minutest 
phenomena,  those  of  light  and  colour.  To  him,  indeed, 
are  owing  some  of  the  observations  and  methods  by 
which  subsequently  the  greatest  and  the  smallest  meas- 
urements of  natural  objects  have  been  carried  out.  But 
in  exact  science  the  deeper  philosophical  meanings  dis- 
appear where  the  strict  mathematical  deductions  point 
to  definite  conceptions,  mark  certain  fixed  paths  of 
research,  and  promise  definite  results.  The  eighteenth 
century  gradually  settled  down  to  a  wholesale  adoption 
of  the  gravitation  theory — looked  upon  space  as  empty, 
upon  matter  as  subject  to  a  definite  though  changing 
distribution  in  space,  and  upon  the  forces  of  nature  as 
attached  to  certain  moving  centres,  between  which  only 
a  mathematical,  but  no  intelligible  physical,  connection 


— whether  it  was  empty  or  full — 
the  two  doctrines  came  into  conflict. 
That  Newton's  position  was  not  a 
final,  but  only  a  provisional  one, 
was  overlooked  ;  he  was  accused  of 
introducing  again  the  occult  quali- 


ties of  the  scholastic  philosophy,  and 
a  great  fight  was  started  against  his 
views  in  the  Academy  of  Sciences, 
where  Descartes'  philosophy  reigned 
supreme. 


340 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


could  be  traced.1  What  to  some  contemporaries  of  Newton, 
and  even  to  Newton  himself,  seemed  an  absurdity — that 
action  could  take  place  at  a  distance 2 — became  through 


1  Voltaire,  who  did  not  dive  very 
deep  into  the  teachings  of  Newton, 
gives  a  graphic  description  of  the 
different  opinions  then  current  in 
English  and  French  learned  circles. 
In   his   'Lettres  sur   les   Anglais,' 
written  about  the  time  of  the  death 
of  Newton,  after  having  discoursed 
on    Quakerism,    the    Church    and 
Government,  on  vaccination,  Bacon 
and  Locke,  he  devotes  four  chapters 
to  the  philosophy  of  Newton,  which 
he  contrasts  with  that  of  Descartes. 
' '  Un  Francais  qui  arrive  a  Londres 
trouve  les  choses  bieu  changees  en 
philosophic,    comme    dans    tout  le 
reste.     II  a  laiss^  le  monde  plein,  il 
le  trouve  vide.  Paris  on  voit 
1'univers  compose*  de  tourbillons  de 
matiere  subtile,  a  Londres  on  ne 
voit  rien  de  cela.     Chez  nous  c'est 
la  pression  de  la  lune  qui  cause  le 
flux   de  la  mer ;   chez  les  Anglais 
c'est  la   mer   qui   gravite   vers    la 
lune.    .    .    .    Chez  vos  Carte"siens 
tout  se  fait  par  une  impulsion  qu'on 
ne  comprend  guere  ;  chez  M.  New- 
ton c'est  par  une  attraction  dont  on 
ne  connait  pas  mieux  la  cause.  .  .  . 
Descartes  assure  encore  que  1'eten- 
due  seule  fait  la  matiere,  Newton  y 
ajoute  la  solidite"  (lettre  xiv.) 

2  "  You  sometimes  speak  of  grav- 
ity  as   essential    and    inherent    to 
matter.     Pray,  do  not  ascribe  that 
notion  to  me  ;  for  the  cause  of  grav- 
ity is  what  I  do   not  pretend   to 
know"  (Newton's  2nd  letter  to  Bent- 
ley,  17th  January  1692-93).     "  It  is 
inconceivable  that  inanimate  brute 
matter  should,  without  the  media- 
tion of  something  else,  which  is  not 
material,   operate  upon  and  affect 
other  matter  without  mutual  con- 
tact, as  it  must  be,  if  gravitation, 
in  the  sense  of  Epicurus,  be  essential 
and  inherent  in  it.    And  this  is  one 


reason  why  I  desired  you  would  not 
ascribe  innate  gravity  to  me.  That 
gravity  should  be  innate,  inherent, 
and  essential  to  matter,  so  that  one 
body  may  act  upon  another  at  a 
distance  through  a  vacuum,  without 
the  mediation  of  anything  else,  by 
and  through  which  their  action  and 
force  may  be  conveyed  from  one  to 
another,  is  to  me  so  great  an  ab- 
surdity that  I  believe  no  man,  who 
has  in  philosophical  matters  a  com- 
petent faculty  of  thinking,  can  ever 
fall  into  it.  Gravity  must  be  caused 
by  an  agent  acting  constantly  ac- 
cording to  certain  laws;  but  whether 
this  agent  be  material  or  immaterial, 
I  have  left  to  the  consideration  of 
my  readers  "  (3rd  letter  to  Bentley, 
5th  February  1692-93).  And  in 
the  fifth  answer  to  Leibniz  (pub- 
lished after  Leibniz's  death)  Clarke 
says  :  ' '  That  the  sun  attracts  the 
earth  .  .  .  — that  is,  that  the  earth 
and  sun  gravitate  towards  each 
other,  or  tend  towards  each  other, 
with  a  force  which  is  in  a  direct 
proportion  of  their  masses,  .  .  . 
and  in  an  inverse  duplicate  propor- 
tion of  their  distances,  and  that  the 
space  betwixt  them  is  void — that  is, 
has  nothing  in  it  which  sensibly  re- 
sists the  motion  of  bodies  passing 
transversely  through :  all  this  is 
nothing  but  a  phenomenon  or  actual 
matter  of  fact,  found  by  experience. 
That  this  phenomenon  is  not  pro- 
duced sans  moycn — that  is,  without 
some  cause  capable  of  producing 
such  an  effect — is  undoubtedly  true. 
Philosophers  therefore  may  search 
after  and  discover  that  cause,  if 
they  can  ;  be  it  mechanical  or  not 
mechanical.  .  .  .  The  phenomenon 
itself,  the  attraction,  gravitation,  or 
tendency  of  bodies  towards  each 
other,  and  the  laws  or  proportions 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        341 

a  century  of  confirming  thought,  observation,  and  calcula- 
tion an  adopted  axiom,  and  the  accepted  formula  of  all 
physical  explanations.  For  a  time,  indeed,  the  exact 
formula  of  gravitation  seemed  liable  to  some  correction, 
but  gradually  the  apparent  anomalies  disappeared,  and 
even  in  our  century  none  of  the  many  attempts  to  modify 
the  gravitation  formula,  to  look  upon  it  as  merely  an  ap- 
proximation, or  to  go  behind  it  and  find  some  more  general 
relation  from  which  it  could  be  deduced,  have  been  gen- 
erally useful  or  acceptable.1  It  still  stands  there  as  the 
only  universally  accepted  mathematical  expression  which 
corresponds  to  a  general  physical  property  of  natural 
objects. 

Two  different  lines  of  thought  combined  to  give  the 
formula  of  Newton  a  still  wider  importance  than  its 
author  primarily  intended,  or  than  it  has  been  found 
possible  to  maintain  in  the  course  of  further  inquiry.  The 
first  was  the  ancient  philosophical  idea  of  attraction,  which, 
without  being  mathematically  defined  and  practically  use- 
ful, had  nevertheless,  from  the  dawn  of  Greek  speculation 


of  that  tendency,  are  now  suffici- 
ently known  by  observations  and 
experiments.  If  this  or  any  other 
learned  author  can  by  the  laws  of 


these  different  attempts  will  be 
found  in  the  writings  of  C.  Isen- 
krahe,  '  Das  Rathsel  von  der 
Schwerkraf t, '  Braunschweig,  1879  ; 


mechanism  explain  these  phenom-   ;    "Euler's  Theorie  von  der  Ursache 
ena,  he  will  not  only  not  be  con-    |   der  Gravitation,"  in  '  Zeitschrif  t  f  iir 


tradicted,  but  will,  moreover,  have 
the  abundant  thanks  of  the  learned 
world.  But  in  the  meantime,  to 
compare  gravitation,  which  is  a  phe- 
nomenon or  actual  matter  of  fact, 
with  Epicurus'  declination  of  atoms 
seems  to  be  a  very  extraordinary 
method  of  reasoning"  (§§  118-124, 
Leibniz's  '  Philosophische  Schrif- 
ten,'  by  Gerhardt,  Berlin,  1890,  vol. 
vii.  p.  439  sq. ) 

1  A    very  complete    account    of 


Mathematik  und  Physik,'  vol.  xxvi. ; 
'Ueber  die  Fernkraft,'  Leipzig, 
1889  ;  "Ueber  die  Zuriickfiihrung 
der  Schwere  auf  Absorption,"  in 
'  Abhandlungen  zur  Geschichte  der 
Mathematik,'  vol.  vi.,  Leipzig,  Teub- 
ner,  1892.  See  also  as  bearing  on 
this  subject,  Paul  du  Bois-Reymond, 
'  Ueber  die  Grundlagen  derErkennt- 
niss  in  den  exacten  Wissenschaft- 
en,'  Tubingen,  1890. 


342  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

and  all  through  ancient  and  mediaeval  philosophy,  figured 

as  one  of  the  occult  causes  or  forces  which  regulate  the 

behaviour  of  living  and  dead  matter.     That  the  force  of 

as.        attraction  alone  would  result  in  an  accumulation  of  all 

Attraction 

matter  in  one  body  was  of  course  recognised,  and  a  second 
arbitrary  and  occult  force — that  of  repulsion — was  intro- 
duced as  a  counteracting  or  balancing  agent. 

In  Newton's  system  of  the  universe  the  balancing  force 
was  found  to  be  that  of  an  inherent  initial  motion  which 
matter,  in  consequence  of  its  mass  or  inertia,  maiutained 
in  addition  to  the  motion  due  to  gravitation.  If  motion 
and  inertia  were  able  to  account  for  the  apparent  repul- 
sion of  bodies  at  a  distance,  it  might  be  that  they  could 
also  account  for  their  apparent  attraction.  This  idea, 
though  expressed  about  the  time  when  the  Newtonian 
gravitation  formula  was  established,  did  not  meet  with 
serious  attention  till  far  on  in  our  century  other  lines  of 
thought  led  to  similar  views.1  The  phenomena  of  attrac- 

1  Newton  himself  seems  to  have  however,  in  the  course  of  the  next 
looked  for  a  mechanical  explanation  decade  found  it  more  useful  to  work 
of  gravitation.  Long  before  the  out  the  mathematical  conclusions 


publication   of  the   'Principia'  he 
laid    before  the    Royal   Society  a 


to  be  drawn  from  the  phenomenon 
of  gravitation,  which  was  a  fact  and 


paper    containing     "  a    hypothesis  !   not  a  hypothesis,  he  abandoned  the 

explaining  the  properties  of  light"  '   metaphysical   part  of  the  subject, 

by  the  assumption  of  an  "  setherial  \  the  question  how  gravitation   was 

medium,  much  of  the  same  consti-  j   to  be  explained,  "finding"  (as  Mac- 

tution    with    air,    but    far    rarer,  laurin  says  in  his  account  of  Xew- 

subtiler,  and  more  strongly  elastic  "  ton's  discoveries)  "  that  he  was  not 

(Letter  to  Oldenburg,  January  25,  able,  from  experiment  and  obser- 

1675-76,  given  in  Brewster's  '  Me-  vation,    to   give  a  satisfactory  ac- 

raoirs  of   Sir   I.    Xewton,'   vol.    L  '  count    of    this    medium    and    the 

p.  390  sqq.),  which  might  explain  |  manner  of  its  operation  in  produc- 

magnetic  and  electric  phenomena,  ing  the  chief  phenomena  of  nature/' 

as  well  as  those  of  gravitation,  and  I   And  in  his  letter  to  Boyle,  as  well 

especially  light.      And  in  a  letter  as  in  a  later  one  to  Halley  (20th 

to  Robert  Boyle,  of  28th  February  j  June  1886,  Brewster,  vol.  L  p.  439), 

1678-79  (Brewster,  vol.  i.  p.  409),  he  carefully  distinguishes  between 

he  reverts  to  this  subject.     Having,  the  results  of  the  '  Principia '  and 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        343 

tion  and  repulsion  at  a  distance  rather  received  additional 
weight  and  importance  when,  following  Newton's  cosmical 
measurements,  Cavendish  and  Coulomb,  towards  the  end 


the  mere  framing  of  hypotheses 
and  conjectures,  for  which  he  pro- 
fesses to  have  little  fancy,  though 
"  the  heads  of  some  great  virtuosos 
run  much  upon  hypotheses " ;  and 
he  describes  his  earlier  speculations 
as  "  guesses  which  I  did  not  rely 
on."  In  fact,  the  elaboration  of 
the  theorems  contained  in  the 
'  Principia '  marks  the  transition 
from  the  metaphysical  to  the  exact 
or  scientific  treatment  of  natural 
phenomena.  Before  Newton  showed 
the  far-reaching  consequences,  the 
unexpected  grasp  of  a  simple  mathe- 
matical formula  in  combining  facts 
apparently  disconnected,  no  one 
could  have  suspected  that  such 
would  be  possible,  and  it  is  not  to 
be  wondered  at  that  when  once 
philosophers  realised  the  power  of 
such  formula),  an  opposite  move- 
ment set  in  through  which  mathe- 
matical processes  were  extolled  at 
the  expense  of  experiment  and 
observation  on  the  one  side,  and 
of  philosophical  reasoning  on  the 
other.  Newton  himself  never  fell 
into  this  error.  He  knew  well  the 
importance  of  observation,  and  he 
retained  to  the  end  of  his  life  a 
great  interest  in  the  philosophical 
or  metaphysical  problems  which  lay 
beyond  or  behind  the  mathemati- 
cal statement  ;  he  carefully  distin- 
guished between  the  vis  gravitatis 
and  the  causa  gravitatis.  Two  other 
great  thinkers,  second  only  to  New- 
ton himself,  took  up  a  similar  posi- 
tion to  the  law  of  gravitation. 
Whilst  firmly  believing  in  it,  they 
considered  it  to  be  not  an  ultimate 
law  of  nature,  a  causa  occulta,  but 
believed  that  it  must  be  possible  to 
derive  it  from  some  mechanical 
properties  of  matter.  The  one  was 
older  than  Newton.  It  was  Huy- 


gens  (1629-95)  who  through  his 
analysis  of  centrifugal  forces  (1673) 
had  done  so  much  to  pave  the  way 
for  Newton's  own  work.  In  1690, 
after  having  paid  a  visit  to  England 
in  order  to  become  more  intimately 
acquainted  with  Newton's  work,  he 
published  at  Leydeii  his  '  Discours 
sur  la  Cause  de  la  Pesanteur,'  a 
treatise  which  was  little  noticed  at 
the  time,  and  in  which  he  is  sup- 
posed to  have  revived  the  vortices 
of  Descartes.  Those  who  have  care- 
fully examined  it  (Fritsch, '  Theorie 
der  Newtou'schen  Gravitation,'  &c., 
Konigsberg,  1874 ;  and  Isenkrahe, 
'  Das  Rathsel  von  der  Schwerkraft,' 
p.  87,  &c.),  find  that  Huygens  re- 
verted to  his  conception  of  a  mate- 
rial fluid,  an  ether,  such  as  he  had 
suggested  for  the  explanation  of 
optical  phenomena,  "which  sur- 
rounds the  earth  up  to  very  great 
distances,  which  consists  of  the 
minutest  particles,  which  fly  about 
in  the  most  different  ways  in  all 
directions  with  tearing  velocity  " — 
an  anticipation  surely  of  Lesage's 
"ultramundane  corpuscles."  The 
other  great  thinker  who,  whilst 
firmly  believing  in  Newton's  law, 
sought  for  a  mechanical  explanation 
of  it,  was  Leonhard  Euler  (1707-83). 
In  his  ether  theory,  to  which  he 
reverts  frequently,  he  made  an 
attempt  to  explain  the  various 
physical  agencies,  among  them 
gravitation  (1743,  in  his  '  Disser- 
tatio  de  Magneto,'  which  received 
in  1744  the  prize  offered  by  the 
Paris  Academy),  by  the  pressure  of 
the  ether.  He  admits  the  difficulty 
of  the  problem,  but  insists  upon  the 
necessity  of  finding  a  mechanical 
cause  for  gravitation.  See  Isen- 
krahe in  '  Zeitschrift  fiir  Mathe- 
matik  und  Physik,'  vol.  xxvi.  ;  but 


344  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

24.        of  the  last  century,  subjected  the  less  universal  terrestrial 

EJectrical 

and  mag-      phenomena  of  magnetic  and  electnc  action  to  exact  mea- 

netic  action. 

surements,  finding  that  a  formula  corresponding  to  the 
gravitation  formula  described  them  with  surprising  ac- 
curacy, with  this  remarkable  difference,  that  here  not  only 
attractive  but  also  repulsive  forces,  following  the  same 
mathematical  relations  as  to  mass  and  distance,  came  into 
play.  To  these  confirmatory  discoveries  must  be  added 
the  measurement  of  the  intensity  of  radiations  which 
proceed  from  centres,  such  as  those  of  light  and  heat, 
made  by  various  philosophers  during  the  latter  half  of 
the  last  century.  Newton,  and  his  great  successor  La- 
place more  than  a  century  after  him,  both  favoured  the 
emission  or  emanation  hypothesis  of  light,  and  it  was 
thus  natural  to  fasten  upon  the  analogy  which  existed 
between  the  intensity  in  which  radiation,  gravitation,  and 
electric  and  magnetic  action  change  with  the  distance 
as.  from  their  respective  centres.  All  these  agencies  came 
emanations,  thus  under  the  general  conception  of  forces  emanating 
from  fixed  centres,  and  spreading  through  space,  in  .the 
proportion  of  the  superficial  area  of  the  spheres  described 
around  their  centres  with  increasing  radii — i.e.,  decreasing 
or  becoming  diluted  in  the  ratio  of  the  squares  of  these 
radii  or  distances.  These  analogies  were  indeed  recognised 
to  be  very  imperfect,  inasmuch  as  light  and  radiant  heat 
occupy  a  measurable  time  to  spread  from  their  centres, 
whereas  the  time  occupied  by  the  force  of  gravitation  is 


especially  Miething,  'L.  Eulers 
Lehre  vom  Aether,'  Berlin,  1894. 
In  the  course  of  this  century  the 


self,  has  again  received  attention 
through  Faraday's.  Maxwell's,  and 
Hertz's  electric  theories,  and  Wm. 


mechanical  theory   of  gravitation,    j   Thomson  (Lord  Kelvin)  has  especi- 
including  the  attempts  of  Lesage,       ally  studied   the  ideas  of  Lesage. 


Euler,  Huygens,  and  Newton  him- 


Of  this  more  later  on. 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        345 


either  exceedingly  small  or  this  force  is  propagated 
instantaneously  through  the  greatest  cosmical  distances 
which  come  under  our  notice.  Then,  again,  light  and 
radiated  heat  spend  themselves  as  they  meet  with  reflect- 
ing or  absorbing  bodies,  whereas  gravitation  does  not 
seem  to  be  affected  by  intervening  or  screening  bodies.1 


1  It  is  now  known  that  this 
screening  effect  exists  likewise  in 
magnetic  and  electric  action.  In 
the  formula  which  expresses  the 
action  at  a  distance  of  magnetic, 
electrical,  and  ponderable  masses, 

,        m.m'    J 
viz.,  f=/j.  — a-,  the  older  view — 

T 

previous  to  Faraday's  researches — 
considered  m  and  m!  the  masses 
(ponderable  or  imponderable),  and 
the  distance  r  to  be  variable,  /u  a 
constant,  corresponding  to  the  gra- 
vitation constant.  As  stated  above, 
the  gravitation  constant  is,  so  far 
as  we  know,  a  real  constant — i.e.,  it 
is  not  affected  by  the  nature  of  the 
medium  which  fills  the  space  inter- 
vening between  m  and  m!,  the  at- 
tractive masses.  Faraday  doubted 
this  ;  but  leaving  gravitation — "  as 
a  relation  by  some  higher  quality  " 
— aside,  he  directed  his  efforts  to 
the  testing  of  the  validity  of  this 
view  as  regards  electric  and  mag- 
netic action.  He  found  that  /x  is 
not  a  real  constant,  but  dependent 
on  the  nature  of  the  medium  and 
the  objects  which  intervene  be- 
tween the  magnetic  and  electric 
masses.  These  researches,  which 
are  probably  the  first  step  in  the 
direction  of  gaining  by  observation 
some  notion  of  the  mechanical 
manner  in  which  action  at  a  dis- 
tance is  brought  about,  begin  with 
the  year  1837  (see  llth  series  of 
*  Experimental  Researches  in  Elec- 
tricity,' No.  1252).  The  result  was 
that  the  "  specific  electric  induction 
for  different  bodies "  was  estab- 
lished, contrary  to  the  ideas  of 


Poisson  and  others  ('Exper.  Res.,' 
No.  1167),  and  the  word  "dielec- 
tric" invented  to  denote  the  "action 
of  the  contiguous  particles  of  the 
insulating  medium"  (No.  1168). 
From  this  point  he  was  led  a 
step  farther,  to  "expect  that  all 
polar  forces  act  in  the  same  general 
manner" — viz.,  by  contiguous  par- 
ticles. Faraday,  however,  is  care- 
ful to  remark  that  by  contiguous 
particles  he  means  those  "  which 
are  next  to  each  other,  not  that 
there  is  no  space  between  them" 
(No.  1665). 

In  1838  Faraday  was  still  doubt- 
ful whether  magnetic  action  was 
similar  in  this  respect  to  statical 
electric  action  ;  but  he  thought  it 
probable  that  it  was  "communi- 
cated by  the  action  of  the  interven- 
ing particles"  (No.  1729),  and  in 
pursuing  this  line  of  thought,  in 
spite  of  many  unsuccessful  trials, 
he  at  last  saw  his  ideas  realised, 
discovered  the  magnetisation  of 
light,  and  invented  the  term  "  dia- 
magnetic"  to  describe  "a  body 
through  which  lines  of  magnetic 
force  are  passing,  and  which  does 
not  by  their  action  assume  the 
usual  magnetic  state"  (1845,  'Ex- 
per. Res.,'  No.  2149).  At  the  end 
of  the  19th  series  of  researches  he 
says:  "In  former  papers  (1838)  I 
proposed  a  theory  of  electrical  in- 
duction founded  on  the  action  of 
contiguous  particles,  .  .  .  and  I 
then  ventured  to  suggest  that  prob- 
ably .  .  .  magnetic  action  was  also 
conveyed  onward  in  a  similar  man- 
ner. At  that  time  I  could  discover 


346 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


26. 

Molecular 
action. 


Nevertheless,  the  fact  that  ,  gravity,  radiation,  and 
electric  and  magnetic  action  appear  as  central  emana- 
tions, decreasing  with  the  square  of  the  distance, — two 
properties  which  lend  themselves  to  mathematical  and 
geometrical  representation, — seemed  to  pave  the  way  for 
further  generalisations.  All  forces  in  nature  were  put 
down  as  central  forces,  either  attractive  or  repulsive,  and 
if  not  following  the  Newtonian  formula,  still  dependent  on 
the  distance  according  to  some  mathematical  expression. 
For  nearly  a  century  theoretical  physics  were  occupied  in 
working  out  the  mathematical  forniulse  expressive  of  these 
ideas,  and  Laplace  himself  promoted  these  attempts  by  the 
Weight  of  his  great  authority.  "We  do  not  possess  the  final 
views  on  this  point  with  which  the  great  mathematician 
intended  to  complete  the  last  edition  of  his  '  Exposition 
du  Systeme  du  Monde ' ;  but  some  of  the  later  chapters  of 
this  work,  treating  of  gravitation  and  molecular  attraction, 
show  us  clearly  in  which  direction  he  looked  for  progress 
in  theoretical  physics.1 


no  peculiar  condition  of  the  inter- 
vening or  diamagnetic  matter  ;  but 
now  that  we  are  able  to  distinguish 
such  an  action ;  .  .  .  now  that 
diamagnetics  are  shown  not  to  be 
indifferent  bodies,  I  feel  still  more 
confidence  in  ...  asking  whether 
it  may  not  be  by  the  action  of  the 
contiguous  or  next  succeeding  par- 
ticles that  the  magnetic  force  is 
carried  onward,"  &c.  (No.  2-143;. 
Faraday  also  made  repeated  experi- 
ments with  the  view  of  determin- 
ing how  the  force  of  gravitation 
is  communicated,  believing  as  little 
as  Newton  did  in  an  actio  in  diftans, 
and  he  was  wont  to  quote  New- 
ton's  words  on  this  matter,  refer- 
ring also  to  Euler's  ether  theory 
(No.  3305). 


1  In  the  fifth  edition  of  the  '  Ex- 
position du  Systeme  du  Monde '  La- 
place had  suppressed  these  chapters, 
and  had  announced  his  intention 
"to  unite  the  principal  results  of 
the  application  of  analysis  to  phe- 
nomena depending  on  a  molecular 
action  differing  from  universal  at- 
traction" into  a  special  treatise 
which  should  form  a  sequel  to  the 
'Exposition,'  &c.  This  project  was 
never  carried  out  (see  "avertisse- 
ment  au  sixieme  edition  de  '  TEx- 
position '  ").  The  success  which 
attended  Laplace's  attempts  to  ex- 
plain double  refraction  and  aber- 
ration of  light  (following  Newton's 
suggestions  in  the  '  Principia '  and 
'  Optics '}  as  well  as  capillary  pheno- 
mena (following  Haukesbee)  left  no 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        347 


The  great  prominence,  given  by  Laplace  to  the  gravita- 
tional explanation  of  all  natural  phenomena,  the  fact  that 
all  the  observable  movements  of  the  universe,  the  shape 
and  size  of  the  moving  masses,  and  the  orbits  they  de- 
scribe, as  well  as  many  phenomena  observable  on  the 
surface  of  our  globe,  such  as  the  aberration  and  refraction 
of  light,  the  phenomena  of  the  tides,  of  atmospheric  pres- 
sure, and  some  of  the  more  important  molecular  properties 
of  matter,  could  be  perfectly  or  approximately  described, 
calculated,  and  predicted  by  gravitation  or  analogous  at- 
tractions, gave  to  what  we  may  call — following  a  hint 
of  Clerk  Maxwell's — the  astronomical  method  l  of  con- 


doubt  in  his  mind  that  such  pheno- 
mena "are  owing  to  attractive  and 
repulsive  forces  between  molecule 
and  molecule"  ('Expos.,'  6me  ed., 
p.  328).  He  saw  in  molecular  at- 
traction the  cause  of  the  solidity  of 
bodies,  of  chemical  affinities,  and  of 
the  properties  of  chemical  satura- 
tion, which  Berthollet  had  developed 
about  that  time  ('Expos.,'  p.  360)  ; 
he  thinks  it  likely  that  the  law  of 
molecular  attraction  is  the  same  for 
all  bodies,  and  he  finally  dwells  on 
the  question  whether  the  attraction 
of  gravity  and  molecular  attraction 
could  be  united  under  one  common 
law  or  expression  (p.  363),  and 
throws  out  the  idea  that  thus  the 
phenomena  of  physics  and  astro- 
nomy might  be  brought  under  one 
general  law,  adding,  however,  signi- 
ficantly, "Mais  1'impossibilite  de 
connaitre  les  figures  des  molecules 
et  leurs  distances  mutuelles,  rend 
ces  explications  vagues  et  inutiles  a 
1'avancement  des  sciences." 

1  "Cavendish,  Coulomb,  and 
Poisson,  the  founders  of  the  exact 
sciences  of  electricity  and  magnet- 
ism, paid  no  regard  to  those  old 
notions  of  '  magnetic  effluvia '  and 
'  electric  atmospheres  '  which  had 


been  put  forth  in  the  previous 
century,  but  turned  their  undivided 
attention  to  the  determination  of 
the  law  of  force,  according  to  which 
electrified  and  magnetised  bodies 
attract  or  repel  each  other.  In  this 
way  the  true  laws  of  these  actions 
were  discovered,  and  this  was  done 
by  men  who  never  doubted  that 
the  action  took  place  at  a  distance, 
without  the  intervention  of  any 
medium,  and  who  would  have  re- 
garded the  discovery  of  such  a 
medium  as  complicating  rather 
than  as  explaining  the  undoubted 
phenomena  of  attraction.  .  .  . 
Ampere,  by  a  combination  of 
mathematical  skill  with  experi- 
mental ingenuity,  first  proved  that 
two  electric  currents  act  on  one 
another,  and  then  analysed  this 
action  into  the  resultant  of  a 
system  of  push  -  and  -  pull  forces 
between  the  elementary  parts  of 
these  currents.  .  .  .  Whereas  the 
general  course  of  scientific  method 
then  consisted  in  the  application 
of  the  ideas  of  mathematics  and 
astronomy  to  each  new  investiga- 
tion in  turn,  Faraday  seems  to 
have  had  no  opportunity  of  ac- 
quiring a  technical  knowledge  of 


348  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

•27.       sidering  nature  a  great  impetus.     As  we  have  seen,  it 

The  astro- 

nomicai       was  entirely  an  outcome  or  .N  ewton  s  great  discovery. 

view. 

SS^tnd  ^  *s  sometimes  useful  to  distinguish  between  cosmical, 
molar,  and  molecular  phenomena ;  it  is,  however,  well  to 
note  that  this  distinction  is  a  popular  or  practical,  not  a 
scientific  one.  The  question,  in  how  far  pure  magnitude 
affects  the  appearance  and  relations  of  the  parts  or  ele- 
ments of  which  the  universe  is  composed,  is  indeed  of 
great  scientific  interest,  but  it  has  not  yet  received  a 
definite  answer.  In  the  meantime  we  can  use  the  term 
cosmical  for  such  magnitudes  of  space,  mass,  or  time  as 
far  transcend  our  own  powers  of  direct  measurement  by 
the  foot-rule,  the  balance,  and  the  timepiece,  and  still 
more,  our  powers  of  direct  action :  those  dimensions  com- 
pared with  which  our  own  homes  and  actions  absolutely 
disappear.  "We  will  call  molar  those  masses  which  we 
can  handle  directly,  those  dimensions  in  which  we  build 
our  own  homes  and  pass  our  own  lives.  And  we  will 
call  molecular  those  sizes  and  masses  which  on  the  other 
side  are  so  small  that  the  utmost  powers  of  the  micro- 
scope and  the  dividing  machine  fail  to  make  them  directly 
visible,  still  less  tangible  or  manageable  for  our  active 
powers.  The  lines  which  limit  these  three  regions  are 
indeed  neither  fixed  nor  fixable ;  the  middle  region,  which 


mathematics,  and  his  knowledge  of 
astronomy  was  mainly  derived  from 
books.  .  .  .  Thus  Faraday  was  de- 
barred from  following  the  course 


of  the  learned"  (Clerk  Maxwell, 
"Action  at  a  Distance,"  'Proceed- 
ings of  the  Royal  Institution,'  vol. 
viL  Reprinted  in  '  Scientific  Papers,' 


of  thought  which  had  led  to  the  Cambridge,  1890,  voL  ii  p.  317  «?. 

achievements  of  the  French  philos-  Cf.  also  vol.  L  p.  156).     Du  Bois- 

ophers,  and  was  obliged  to  explain  Reymond    uses    the    term   "  astro- 

the  phenomena  to  himself  by  means  nomicai  knowledge ;'  in  a  somewhat 

of  a  symbolism  which  he  could  un-  wider  sense  in  his  discourse  "  Ueber 

derstand,  instead  of  adopting  what  die  Grenzen  des  Xaturerkennens  " 

had  hitherto  been  the  only  tongue  ('Reden,'  vol.  i.  p.  120). 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW    OF   NATURE.        349 


we  may  call  our  own  home,  seems  to  be  extending  through 
improved  means  of  seeing  and  handling;  still  every  one 
has  a  vague  notion,  and  science  has  supported  this  notion, 
that  there  are  certain  limits,  marking  the  immeasurably 
large  and  the  immeasurably  small,  which  we  cannot  tran- 
scend. Now  it  is  a  question  of  great  scientific  interest 
to  what  extent  mere  enlargement,  such  as  the  microscope 
makes  familiar  to  us,  would  essentially  alter  the  behaviour 
and  appearance  of  things  natural.  Would  the  planetary 
or  stellar  systems,  reduced  in  size  many  million  times, 
present  an  aspect  similar  to  the  view  we  here  enjoy  of  the 
inanimate  matter  on  the  surface  of  our  earth,  and  would 
the  molecular  structure  of  microscopic  objects,  many  times 
enlarged,  differ  essentially  from  that  aspect  ?  Our  present 
knowledge  would  lead  us  to  say  they  would  essentially 
differ.  Certain  phenomena  or  modes  of  motion  seem,  so 
far  as  we  know,  essentially  characteristic  of  the  molecular, 
others  of  the  molar,  others  again  of  the  cosmical  world.1 


1  Laplace  has  made  a  significant 
remark  on  this  point.  See  '  Ex- 
position du  Systeme  du  Monde,' 
6  ed.,  p.  319  sq.  :  "La  loi  de  la 
pesanteur  reciproque  au  carre"  des 
distances  .  .  .  est  celle  de  toutes 
les  Emanations  qui  partent  d'un 
centre,  telle  que  la  lumiere ;  il  pa- 
rait  meme  que  toutes  les  forces  dont 
1'action  se  fait  apercevoir  a  des 
distances  sensibles,  suivent  cette 
loi :  on  a  reconnu  depuis  peu,  que 
les  attractions  et  les  repulsions 
clectriques  et  magnetiques  decrois- 
sent  en  raison  du  carrE  des  dis- 
tances, en  sorte  que  toutes  ces 
forces  ne  s'affaiblissent  en  se  pro- 
pageant,que  parcequ'elles  s'Etendent 
comme  la  lumiere  ;  leurs  quantites 
etant  les  memes  sur  les  diverses 
surfaces  spheYiques  que  Ton  peut 


imagiuer  autour  de  leurs  foyers. 
Une  proprie'te  remarquable  de  cette 
loi  de  la  nature  est  que  si  les 
dimensions  de  tous  les  corps  de  cet 
univers,  leurs  distances  mutuelles 
et  leurs  vitesses,  venaient  h,  aug- 
menter  ou  a  diminuer  proportion- 
ellement ;  ils  decriraient  des  courbes 
entierement  semblables  a  celles, 
qu'ils  de"crivent,  et  leurs  apparences 
seraient  exactement  les  memes  ;  car 
les  forces,  qui  les  animent,  e"taut  le 
resultat  d'attractions  proportion- 
elles  aux  masses  divisees  par  le  carre 
des  distances,  elles  augmenteraient 
ou  diminueraient  proportiouelle- 
ment  aux  dimensions  du  nouvel 
univers.  On  voit  en  meme  temps, 
que  cette  proprie'te  ue  peut  apparte- 
nir  qu'h  la  loi  de  la  nature.  Ainsi, 
les  apparences  des  mouvemeuts  de 


350  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

as.        And  we  cannot  but  be  struck  by  the  fact  that  only  those 

Special 

interest       dimensions  which  we  call  molar  appear  to  be  the  abode 

attached 

dtaens^ons  °^  living  an(l  conscious  beings.  The  cosmical  world  has, 
so  far  as  we  know,  no  inhabitant  which  can  behold  it  in 
the  same  way  as  man  beholds  this  planet,  and  the  same 
obtains  so  far  as  we  are  acquainted  with  the  molecular 
world.  So  far  as  our  knowledge  goes  and  is  likely  ever 
to  reach,  a  special  importance  or  dignity  will  therefore 
always  belong  to  molar  dimensions  and  masses.  The  pro- 
cess by  which  we  try  to  picture  to  ourselves  in  tracings  and 
models,  constructed  in  molar  dimensions,  the  behaviour 
and  appearance  of  cosmical  as  well  as  molecular  masses  will 
always  recommend  itself,  not  only  as  the  most  practical,  but 
likewise  as  the  most  interesting  and  plausible,  for  only  by 
this  procedure  do  these  unreachable  worlds  become  amen- 
able to  direct  observation  and  to  the  processes  of  experi- 
ment in  the  physical  laboratory.  It  seems  prima  facie 
that  the  wealth  of  phenomena  and  the  variety  of  different 
kinds  of  motion  decrease  as  we  ascend  into  the  cosmical, 
or  as  we  descend  into  the  molecular  world,  giving  way 
in  the  former  to  essentially  uniform,  though  to  many 
times  multiplied  modes  of  motion,  and  disappearing  in 

I'univers  sont  inde'pendantes  de  ses  a   centre   like    the   sun   would    be 
dimensions   absolues,    cotnme  elles          F        „,         rn        .  . 

le    sont,    du    mouvement    absolu,   j  K^=K       x^«    wluch    1S    only 
qu'il  peut  avoir  dans  1'espace ;  et  m 

nous  ne  pouvons  observer  et  con-  »    times    the    acceleration    ^-,    i 

naitre  que  des  rapports."     This  is   [  n  =  2.     in  another  passage  Laplace 

easily  seen.     For  if  in  the  formula  repeat3    the    above    statement    in 

/=^^,    the    dimensions    be    all  slightly   different   words:    "L'uni- 

vers  reduit  successivemeut  jusqu'au 

multiplied  by  K,  we  get  the  new   ;  plus  petit  espace  imaginable,  offrir- 

foramk  *=£*-»  X—,    and   the  !  ?ic  toujours  les  memes  apparences 

r»  a  ses  observateurs     (p.  440).     That 

acceleration  of  a  body  moving  round  this  would  not  apply  to  molecular 

attractions  or  repulsions  is  evident. 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        351 


the  latter  in  stable  and  self-repeating  averages.  Pos- 
sessed therefore,  as  we  seem  to  be,  of  the  greatest  wealth 
and  variety  of  observations  and  notions,  we  may — perhaps 
erroneously — conclude  that  we  can  grasp  the  simpler 
cosmical  and  molecular  movements  and  phenomena  by 
starting  from  molar,  physical,  or  mechanical  models.1 


1  English  naturalists  have  always 
excelled  in  this  line  of  investigation, 
whereas  foreign  scientific  literature 
has  been  rich  in  purely  mathemati- 
cal deductions  from  formulae  which 
contained  no  construirbare  Vorstel- 
lung.  And  it  is  interesting  to  note 
that  both  lines  of  thought  go  back 
to  Newton.  Whereas  Newton  him- 
self believed  in  the  possibility  of  a 
mechanical  explanation  or  represen- 
tation of  the  gravitation  formula, 
the  second  edition  of  the  '  Prin- 
cipia '  by  Cotes  can  be  looked  upon 
as  sanctioning  the  view  that  gravi- 
tation is  an  ultimate  quality  which 
must  be  accepted  as  such  ;  and  as 
it  was  the  second  edition  through 
which  Newton's  ideas  became  large- 
ly known  on  the  Continent,  it  is 
not  surprising  that  he  was  there 
accused  of  reintroducing  the  quali- 
tates  occultce  of  the  older  metaphys- 
ics, which  Descartes  and  others  had 
successfully  banished.  Clerk  Max- 
well says  ("  Action  at  a  Distance," 
'Scient.  Pap.,'  vol.  ii.  p.  316): 
"  The  doctrine  of  direct  action  at 
a  distance  cannot  claim  for  its 
author  the  discoverer  of  universal 
gravitation.  It  was  first  asserted 
by  Roger  Cotes  in  his  preface  to 
the  '  Principia,'  which  he  edited 
during  Newton's  life.  According 
to  Cotes  it  is  by  experience  that 
we  learn  that  all  bodies  gravitate. 
We  do  not  learn  in  any  other  way 
that  they  are  extended,  movable, 
or  solid.  Gravitation,  therefore, 
has  as  much  right  to  be  considered 
an  essential  property  of  matter  as 
extension,  mobility,  or  impenetra- 


bility. And  when  the  Newtonian 
philosophy  gained  ground  in  Europe, 
it  was  the  opinion  of  Cotes  rather 
than  that  of  Newton  that  became 
most  prevalent."  In  fact,  philoso- 
phers could  be  divided  into  two 
classes — those  who  took  the  fact 
of  gravity  or  the  wider  idea  of  a 
universal  attraction  as  a  beginning, 
and  drew  from  this  beginning  all 
the  possible  mathematical  and  ex- 
perimental consequences  which  they 
could  think  of ;  and  those  who, 
whilst  admitting  this  process  as  a 
legitimate  one,  thought  it  neces- 
sary to  go  behind  the  assumed 
beginning  and  find  a  still  more 
hidden  mechanical  reason  for  this 
admitted  property.  To  the  latter 
class  belonged  Newton  himself, 
Huygens,  Euler,  and  in  modern 
times  notably  Faraday  and  his  fol- 
lowers ;  to  the  former  class  be- 
longed Daniel  Bernoulli,  who  wrote 
to  Euler,  4th  February  1744,  refer- 
ring to  the  ether  theory  of  the  lat- 
ter :  "  Moreover,  I  believe  both  that 
the  ether  is  gravis  versus  solcm  and 
the  air  versus  terram,  and  I  cannot 
conceal  from  you  that  on  these 
points  I  am  a  perfect  Newtonian, 
and  I  am  surprised  that  you  ad- 
here so  long  to  the  principiis  Car- 
tcsianis  ;  there  is  possibly  some  feel- 
ing in  the  matter.  If  God  has  been 
able  to  create  an  animam  whose  na- 
ture is  unknown  to  us,  He  has  also 
been  able  to  impress  an  attractionem 
universalem  materue,  though  such  is 
attractio  supra  captum,  whereas  the 
principia  C'artcsiana  involve  always 
something  contra  captum "  (see 


352 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


29.  I  may,  in  passing,  mention  here  that  in  the  course  of 

Geometrical  ...  , 

axioms,  our  century  certain  views  have  been  put  forward  in  pure 
mathematics,  or  rather  in  geometry,  which  make  it  con- 
ceivable, if  not  probable,  that  our  ideas  of  space  might 
not  apply  to  immeasurably  small  or  to  immeasurably 
large  dimensions.1  Should  the  future  progress  of  thought 


Miething,  'L.  Euler's  Lehre  vom 
Aether,'  p.  30).  In  quite  recent 
times  a  similar  position  has  again 
been  taken  up  by  Paul  du  Bois- 
Reymond  in  his  essay  "Ueber  die 
Unbegreiflichkeit  der  Fernkraft," 
in  the  '  Xaturwissenschaftliche 
Rundschau'  (vol.  iii  No.  14),  and 
in  his  posthumous  work,  'Ueber 
die  Grundlagen  der  Erkenntniss  in 
den  exacten  Wissenschaf ten '  (Tu- 
bingen, 1890),  in  which  he  adds 
action  at  a  distance  as  a  third 
"  ignorabimus  "  or  unknowable  pro- 
blem to  the  two  given  in  his 
brother  Emil's  address,  "  Ueber  die 
Grenzen  des  Naturerkennens " 
(1872,  reprinted  in  'Reden,'  vol. 
L  p.  105).  On  the  Continent, 
about  thirty  years  ago,  the  fruit- 
lessness  of  pursuing  this  problem 
seemed  generally  admitted.  Helm- 
holtz  in  1847  speaks  of  the  initial 
assumption  "  that  all  actions  in  na- 
ture are  to  be  reduced  to  attracting 
and  repelling  forces,  whose  inten- 
sity depends  merely  on  the  distance 
of  points  mutually  acting  on  each 
other"  (actio  in  'distant),  and  Du 
Bois-Reymond  repeats  this  in  1871 
in  his  address.  But  it  is  significant 
that  Helmholtz,  who  (through  his 
memoir  on  vortex  motion  in  185S) 
gave  such  an  impetus  to  the  me- 
chanical explanations  of  molecular 
forces,  modified  his  views  on  this 
point  (see  his  address  on  Magnus, 
1871,  'Vortrage  und  Reden,'  vol. 
ii. ) ;  accordingly  in  the  reprint  of 
his  memoir  of  1847  he  has  accom- 
panied it  with  some  significant  re- 
marks on  the  necessity  of  that 
initial  assumption  (1881,  'Wissen- 


schaftliche  Abhandlungen,'  vol.   i. 
p.  68). 

1  Reimann  was  probably  the  first 
to  give  expression  to  this  line  of 
thought.  His  memoir  on  this  sub- 
ject, "  On  the  Hypotheses  which  lie 
at  the  Foundation  of  Geometry," 
bears  the  date  1S54.  It  was  read 
before  the  Philosophical  Faculty  of 
Gottingen  in  the  presence  and  at  the 
request  of  Gauss,  on  whom  it  made 
a  profound  impression  (see  the  bio- 
graphical notice  on  Reimann  by 
Dedekind,  attached  to  Riemann's 
'Gesammelte  Werke/ Leipzig,  1576  . 
The  memoir  was  not  published  till 
after  Riemann's  death  in  1867.  In 
England  the  late  Prof.  Clifford  in- 
troduced the  subject  to  the  Cam- 
bridge Philosophical  Society  in  1870 : 
"  The  axioms  of  plane  geometry  are 
true  within  the  limits  of  experiment 
on  the  surface  of  a  sheet  of  paper, 
and  yet  we  know  that  the  sheet  is 
really  covered  with  a  number  of 
small  ridges  aud  furrows,  upon 
which  these  axioms  are  not  true. 
Similarly  although  the  axioms  of 
solid  geometry  are  true  within  the 
limits  of  experiment  for  finite  por- 
tions of  our  space,  yet  we  have  no 
reason  to  conclude  that  they  are 
true  for  very  small  portions  ;  and 
if  any  help  can  be  got  thereby  for 
the  explanation  of  physical  pheno- 
mena, we  may  have  reason  to  con- 
clude that  they  are  not  true  for 
very  small  portions  of  space"  (see 
Clifford's  '  Mathematical  Papers,' 
p.  21.  Compare  also  his  lectures 
on  "The  Philosophy  of  the  Pure 
Sciences  "  in  '  Lectures  and  Essays,' 
vol.  i.  p.  295  sq<j.) 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        353 

or  observation  bring  forward  any  indications  that  the 
idea  is  not  only  a  theoretical  possibility,  but  an  actual 
reality,  then  the  mode  of  thought  now  so  successfully 
used — viz.,  that  of  transferring  phenomena  belonging  to 
molar  dimensions,  and  exemplified  in  the  physical  lab- 
oratory, into  cosmic  or  molecular  space  by  a  process  of 
enlarging  or  of  reducing — would  become  inapplicable. 
Mathematics  indeed  would  not  fail,  but  our  ordinary 
geometry  and  the  physical  model  and  mechanism  would 
fail :  we  should  probably  still  be  able  to  calculate, 
though  not  to  represent,  those  phenomena  of  immeasur- 
able dimensions. 

As  it  is,  the  first  great  example  of  calculating  and  pre- 
dicting the  phenomena  of  an  unreachable  world  was 
Newton's  successful  attempt  to  explain  the  movements  , 

of  the  moon,  and  other  cosmical  bodies,  by  using  the 
phenomena  of  falling  bodies  on  the  surface  of  the  earth 
described  by  Galileo  and  Huygens ;  and  he  was  rewarded  so. 

Difficulty  of 

by  the  discovery  of  a  universal  law  of  attraction,  which  measuring 

gravitation 

would  probably  never  have  been  discovered  by  experi-  directly- 
ments  carried  on  within  molar  dimensions,  the  mass  of 
the  earth  being  so  immeasurably  greater  than  that  of 
any  molar  masses  under  our  control.  It  quite  escapes 
our  observation  that  in  the  action  and  reaction  of  the 
falling  stone  the  immensity  of  the  earth's  mass  is  com- 
pensated by  the  vanishing  distance  through  which  the 
earth  moves  when  attracted  by  the  stone.  Thus  the 
astronomical  view  came  to  the  rescue  of  physical  or  molar 
experiments,  helped  to  explain  them,  and  indicated  the 
manner  in  which  cosmical  forces  could  be  measured 
even  on  the  surface  of  the  earth.  The  pendulum  experi- 

VOL.  I.  Z 


354 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


ments  of  Eicher,  Halley,  and  many  others,  the  measure- 
ments of  the  arc  of  the  meridian,  and  Cavendish's  and 
Maskelyne's  experiments,  were  some  of  the  direct  results 
of  the  discovery. 

It  was  natural  that,  having  explained  the  cosmical,  and 
subsequently  many  terrestrial  phenomena,  successfully  by 
the  formula  of  attraction,  Newton  himself,  and  still  more 
Laplace  and  his  school,  should  have  attempted  the  ex- 
planation of  molecular  phenomena  by  similar  methods. 

The  astronomical  view  spread  into  molar  and  molecular 
Newton  himself  made  use  of  the  notion  of 
phenomena,  molecular  attraction l — i.e.,  of  attraction  existing  only  at 


31. 

Astronomi 
cal  view  of      phySlCS. 
molecular 


1  In  the  fourteenth  section  of 
the  first  book  of  the  '  Principia ' 
Newton  is,  however,  careful  to  speak 
always  of  "attractio  vel  impulsus," 
leaving  it  open  to  the  reader  to 
form  his  own  opinion  whether  it  is 
an  action  at  a  distance  or  a  "vis  a 
tergo,"  a  push.  He  says  also  that 
the  particles  of  light  approaching 
solid  bodies  with  a  definite  velo- 
city are  bent,  "  quasi  attracti  in 
eadem  (i.e.,  corpora)."  And  in  the 
twenty  -  third  query  to  the  first 
Latin  edition  of  the  '  Opticks ' 
(1706)  he  says :  "  May  not  the 
small  particles  of  bodies  have  cer- 
tain virtues,  powers,  or  forces  by 
which  they  act  at  some  distance, 
not  only  on  the  rays  of  light,  re- 
flecting, refracting,  or  inflecting 
them,  but  also  on  each  other,  pro- 
ducing various  natural  phenomena  ? 
For  it  is  sufficiently  known  that 
bodies  mutually  act  on  each  other 
through  the  attraction  of  gravity 
and  through  magnetic  and  electric 
virtue.  And  these  examples  show 
what  is  the  order  and  reason  of 
nature,  so  that  it  becomes  very 
probable  that  there  may  be  other 
attractive  forces.  For  nature  is 
very  similar  and  agreeing  to  her- 


self. Through  what  efficient  cause 
these  attractions  are  brought  about 
I  do  not  inquire  here.  What  I 
here  call  attraction  may  well  be 
produced  by  an  impulse  or  in  some 
other  way  unknown  to  us.  I  take 
this  word  attraction  here  in  this 
way,  that  it  be  understood  merely 
to  mean  some  universal  force  with 
which  bodies  try  to  approach  each 
other,  whatever  cause  this  force 
may  have  to  be  attributed  to.  For 
from  the  phenomena  of  nature  it 
behoves  us  first  to  be  taught  which 
bodies  attract  each  other,  and  what 
are  the  laws  and  properties  of  this 
attraction,  before  we  inquire  by 
what  efficient  cause  this  attraction 
is  brought  about.  The  attraction 
of  gravity  and  of  the  magnetic  and 
electric  virtue  extend  to  sufficiently 
large  distances,  so  that  they  fall 
under  the  notice  of  the  vulgar 
senses ;  but  it  may  be  that  there 
are  others  which  are  contained  in 
such  narrow  limits  that  they  have 
so  far  escaped  all  observation." 
And  he  goes  on  to  speak  of  the  de- 
liquescence of  some  salts  and  of 
chemical  combinations  of  finely 
powdered  substances.  And  fur- 
ther on  in  the  same  query,  after 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        355 


very  small  distances — to  explain  the  refraction  and  in- 
flection of  light  passing  from  empty  space,  or  from  the 


referring  to  attractive  forces  acting 
only  at  small  distances,  he  pro- 
ceeds :  ' '  And  as  in  algebra,  when 
the  positive  quantities  disappear 
and  cease,  negative  quantities  be- 
gin ;  so  in  mechanics,  where  attrac- 
tion stops,  there  a  repelling  force 
must  come  sin.  But  that  such  a 
force  exists,  seems  to  follow  from 
the  reflection  and  inflection  of  the 
rays  of  light.  For  the  rays  are 
repelled  by  bodies  in  both  these 
cases,  without  the  immediate  con- 
tact of  the  reflecting  or  inflecting 
body.  And  if  all  this  is  so,  then 
the  whole  of  nature  will  be  very 
simple  and  similar  to  herself ;  per- 
forming all  the  great  motions  of 
the  heavenly  bodies  by  the  attrac- 
tion of  gravity,  which  exists  be- 
tween all  those  bodies,  and  almost 
all  the  smaller  motions  of  their 
particles  through  some  other  at- 
tracting and  repelling  force,  which 
exists  mutually  between  those 
particles"  (' Optice,'  MDCCVI. ,  p. 
341).  The  suggestions  of  Newton 
regarding  forces  of  molecular  di- 
mensions were  taken  up  by  other 
contemporary  writers  and  experi- 
mentalists, and  the  '  Philosophical 
Transactions '  during  the  early 
years  of  the  last  century  contain 
several  memoirs  touching  on  this 
subject,  notably  by  John  Keill 
(1708),  who  refers  to  Newton's 
'  Opticks,'  and  enlarges,  as  does 
also  John  Freind  ( '  Prelectiones 
Chymicre'),  on  the  usefulness  of  the 
idea  of  molecular  attraction  in  ex- 
plaining chemical  and  physiological 
phenomena.  In  the  later  editions 
of  the  '  Opticks,'  evidently  in  con- 
sequence of  the  elaborate  experi- 
ments of  Hauksbee,  Newton  enters 
more  fully  into  the  question  of 
molecular,  especially  capillary,  ac- 
tion ;  and  his  last  query,  No.  31,  is 
quoted  by  Laplace  in  his  '  Theorie 


de  1'Action  capillaire,'  which  forms 
the  supplement  to  the  tenth  book 
of  the  '  Mecanique  celeste. '  I  may 
here  mention  that  as  some  confu- 
sion exists  in  the  different  editions 
of  the  '  Optics '  regarding  the  num- 
bering of  the  "Queries,"  it  is  best 
to  refer  to  Horsley's  Collected  Edi- 
tion of  the  Works  of  Newton, 
where  the  latest  English  edition  is 
reprinted,  and  all  the  variations 
and  additions  noted  from  the  first 
(English)  edition  through  the  sub- 
sequent ones.  The  first  edition 
breaks  off  with  query  16  ;  the  first 
Latin  one  with  query  23,  and  this 
was  in  later  editions  numbered  31, 
a  number  of  new  queries  being  in- 
serted, Nos.  18  to  24,  referring  to 
the  "  probability  of  a  medium  more 
subtle  than  air"  and  the  "me- 
chanical efficient  of  gravity."  This 
was  added  "to  show"  (Newton's 
words  in  preface  dated  16th  July 
1717)  "that  I  do  not  take  gravity 
for  an  essential  property  of  bodies, 
.  .  .  choosing  to  propose  it  by  way 
of  a  question,  because  I  am  not 
yet  satisfied  about  it  by  way  of 
experiments."  We  may  note  that 
this  was  written  a  few  years  after 
the  second  edition  of  the  '  Principia ' 
was  published  by  Cotes,  whose 
preface  did  a  good  deal  to  occasion 
the  misunderstanding  regarding 
Newton's  views  on  gravitation  as  a 
primary  quality  of  matter.  From 
his  correspondence  with  Cotes, 
edited  by  Eddleston  (1850),  we 
know  that  Newton  is  composing 
the  "  Scholium  generale,"  which  is 
added  to  the  second  and  later  edi- 
tions of  the  'Principia,'  had  in- 
tended to  say  "much  more  about 
the  attraction  of  the  small  par- 
ticles of  bodies,"  but  that  on  second 
thoughts  he  abandoned  this  inten- 
tion (p.  147). 


356  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

atmosphere,  into  or  in  the  neighbourhood  of  solid  bodies. 
He  conceived  light  to  be  a  material  substance,  consisting 
of  minute  particles,  propelled  in  straight  lines  from  the 
luminous  centres.  These  small  particles,  when  arriving 
at  or  near  the  surface  of  transparent  bodies,  came  under 
the  influence  of  an  attraction  from  the  substance  of  such 
bodies,  and  Newton  succeeded  in  showing  that  for  rays 
of  light  which  fall  on  transparent  surfaces  at  an  angle, 
the  path  of  the  ray  in  the  body  would  be  deflected  accord- 
ing to  the  rule  experimentally  determined  by  Snell,  and 
published  by  Descartes.  This  application  of  the  idea  of 
attraction,  or  action  at  a  distance,  to  very  small  or  mole- 
cular dimensions,  required  a  modification  of  the  gravita- 
tion formula.  The  first  who  took  an  important  step  farther 
in  this  direction  was  Francis  Hauksbee.  Between  the 
year  1709  and  1713  he  made  a  series  of  experiments  on 
32.  what  is  called  capillary  action.  His  experiments  were 

Capillary 

action.  discussed  by  Newton  in  the  later  editions  of  the  '  Opticks," 
and  followed  by  those  of  Dr  Jurin  in  1718.  Hauksbee,. 
Newton,  Jurin,  and  subsequent  writers,  like  Clairaut,  all 
attributed  these  and  similar  phenomena  to  molecular 
attractions,  and  Laplace  showed  that  for  the  mathematical 
treatment  of  the  subject  a  knowledge  of  the  exact  law 
(corresponding  to  the  Newtonian  law  of  molar  attraction) 
was  unnecessary,  but  that  it  was  necessary  and  sufficient  to 
assume  the  existence  of  an  attraction  of  the  molecules  of 
bodies,  which  decreases  very  rapidly  as  their  distances  in- 
crease, "  so  as  to  become  insensible  at  the  smallest  distances- 
perceptible  by  our  senses." l  The  phenomena  of  atmos- 

1  See  '  Mecanique  celeste,'  vol.  temps,  k  determiner  les  lois  d'at- 
iv.  (1805),  Supplement,  p.  67.  See  traction  qui  representent  ces  phe"- 
also  p.  2  :  "  J'ai  cherche,  il  y  a  long-  !  nomenes  :  de  nouvelles  recherche^ 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF   NATURE.        357 


pheric  refraction  as  well  as  those  of  cohesion  and  adhesion 
of  bodies — i.e.,  the  attraction  of  particles  of  the  same  or  of 
different  matter  under  what  is  commonly  called  contact  or 
at  distances  which  we  call  in  science  molecular — were  thus 
submitted  to  calculation,  and  the  results  brought  largely 
into  harmony  with  experience.1  The  problem  presented 
itself  and  occupied  natural  philosophers  all  through  the 
last  century,  whether  a  more  general  law  of  action  at  a 
distance  could  be  found  which  comprised  the  phenomena 
of  molecular  as  well  as  of  molar  attraction. 

The  most  celebrated  attempt  in  this  direction  is  that       33. 
of  the  Jesuit  Eoger  Boscovich,  who  in  1758  published  an  extension ot 

•flirt    "Voiff  nr»_ 

elaborate  treatise  on  this  subject.2 


the  Newton« 
ian  formula. 


m'ont  enfin  conduit  a  faire  voir 
qu'ils  sont  tous  represented  par  les 
memes  lois  qui  satisfont  aux  phe- 
nomenes  de  la  refraction,  c'est-a-dire 
par  les  lois  dans  lesquelles  1'attrac- 
tion  n'est  sensible  qu'a  des  distances 
insensibles  ;  et  il  en  resulte  une  the- 
orie  complete  de  1'action  capillaire." 
1  The  terms  insensible  and  im- 
perceptible, which  are  commonly 
used  in  these  discussions,  must  be 
taken  with  caution.  It  is  now 
known  that,  though  not  directly 
perceptible  or  sensible,  the  distance 
through  which  molecular  action 
takes  place  is  measurable.  Plateau 
in  Belgium  (1843  and  following 
years)  and  Quincke  in  Germany 
(1868)  made  experiments  on  inde- 
pendent lines,  and  came  to  very 
.similar  results.  The  distance  of 
molecular  action  appears  to  be  about 
the  twenty  thousandth  part  of  a 
millimetre.  See  Clerk  Maxwell's 
article  on  Capillary  Action  in  the 
9th  edition  of  the  'Ency.  Brit.,' 
reprinted  in  '  Scientific  Papers,' 
vol.  ii.  ;  also  Violle's  '  Cours  de 
Physique,'  German  edition,  vol.  L  p. 
591,  &c.,  and  p.  639. 


2  Roger  Joseph  Boscovich,  of  the 
Society  of  Jesus  (1711-87),  took  up 
the  ideas  thrown  out  by  Newton  in 
the  last  query  to  the  '  Opticks,'  and 
published  in  1758  at  Vienna  an 
elaborate  treatise  with  the  title 
'  Theoria  Philosophise  Naturalis  re- 
dacta  ad  unicam  legem  virium  in 
Natura  existentium. '  A  second 
edition  was  published  at  Venice  in 
1763.  His  speculations  begin  with 
the  year  1745,  when  he  hit  upon 
his  general  view  that  all  forces  in 
nature  can  be  reduced  to  the  action 
of  indivisible  and  inextended  atoms, 
endowed  with  inertia  and  with  a 
mutual  force  which  at  vanishing 
distances  is  repulsive,  which  at  in- 
sensible distances  alternates  accord- 
ing to  some  mathematical  formula 
between  repulsion  and  attraction, 
and,  finally,  at  sensible  distances 
becomes  identical  with  Newton's 
force  of  gravitation.  The  general 
form  of  the  curve  which  exhibits 
this  action  at  a  distance  is  given, 
and  the  algebraical  formula  dis- 
cussed, in  the  Supplement.  But 
it  was,  of  course,  impossible  to 
define  the  law  any  further.  The 


358 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


Though  many  of  the  views  contained  in  this  treatise 
were  really  the  same  as  those  embraced  by  a  large  school 
of  Continental  mathematicians  till  far  into  this  century, 


whole  treatise  is  really  more  of  a 
philosophical  than  a  mathematical 
or  experimental  investigation.  A 
large  portion  is  taken  up  in  de- 
fending his  view  against  possible 
objections,  and  in  showing  how  it 
agrees  with  or  differs  from  the 
philosophies  of  Leibniz  and  New- 
ton. Whilst  this  treatise  represents 
in  general  a  view  largely  held  by 
Continental  philosophers  of  nature, 
it  does  not  contain  any  new  mathe- 
matical methods  such  as  the  '  Prin- 
cipia'  contained  before  and  La- 
place's 'Me"canique  celeste'  later,  nor 
does  it  contribute  any  experiments 
such  as  those  works  likewise  con- 
tained and  suggested  to  others. 
lu  fact,  it  is  more  a  metaphysical 
than  an  exact  treatise,  and  as  such 
has  exerted  no  lasting  beneficial 
influence  on  the  progress  of  science. 
"The  eighteenth  century  made  a 
school  of  science  for  itself,  in  which 
for  the  not  unnatural  dogma  of  the 
earlier  schoolmen,  'matter  cannot 
act  where  it  is  not,'  was  substituted 
the  most  fantastic  of  paradoxes, 
contact  does  not  exist.  Boscovich's 
theory  was  the  consummation  of 
the  eighteenth  -  century  school  of 
physical  science.  This  strange  idea 
took  deep  root,  and  from  it  grew 
up  a  barren  tree,  exhausting  the 
soil  and  overshadowing  the  whole 
field  of  molecular  investigation, 
on  which  so  much  unavailing 
labour  was  spent  by  the  great 
mathematicians  of  the  early  part 
of  our  nineteenth  century.  If 
Boscovich's  theory  no  longer  cum- 
bers the  ground,  it  is  because  one 
true  philosopher  required  more  light 
for  tracing  lines  of  electric  force  " 
(Sir  William  Thomson's  Lecture 
before  the  Royal  Institution,  May 
1860.  Reprinted  in  '  Papers  on 


Electrostatics  and  Magnetism,'  2nd 
ed.,  1884,  p.  224).  Nevertheless  it 
is  extraordinary  to  note  that  Bos- 
covich's theory  was  more  popular 
among  British  than  among  Con- 
tinental physicists.  lu  France  the 
book  seems  to  have  been  little  ap- 
preciated, although  Boscovich  was 
well  known  through  his  optical  and 
astronomical  researches  (see  Montu- 
cla's  '  Histoire  des  Mathematiques,' 
vol.  iii.  p.  490,  vol.  iv.  p.  188) ;  and 
his  differences  with  d'Alembert  were 
notorious.  But  French  science  was 
then  occupied  less  with  metaphysi- 
cal theories  than  with  mathematical 
analysis  and  experimental  research. 
In  Germany  the  book  remained 
unknown,  probably  because  Euler's 
authority  favoured  an  opposite 
theory.  In  this  country,  however, 
the  theory  is  often  referred  to  from 
the  time  of  Priestley  ('History  of 
Optics ')  to  Faraday  ("  On  the  Na- 
ture of  Matter,"  ' Phil.  Mag.,'  1844, 
vol.  24),  and  more  recently  Thom- 
son (Lord  Kelvin).  The  last  has 
probably  more  than  any  other  living 
writer  of  similar  eminence  referred 
to  Boscovich,  whose  theory  he  con- 
siders suggestive,  and  we  are  in- 
debted to  him  for  the  first  serious 
attempt  to  establish  by  actual  cal- 
culation the  real  capabilities  of  the 
Boscovich  atoms  in  explaining  the 
properties  of  chemical  molecules, 
their  stability  and  degree  of  satur- 
ation (see  the  Report  of  the 
British  Association  at  Liverpool, 
1896).  In  Scotland  Boscovich's 
theory  was  fully  discussed  in  a 
posthumous  article  on  "Corpuscular 
Forces  "  by  John  Robison,  Professor 
of  Natural  Philosophy  at  Edinburgh, 
and  published  by  Brewster  in  the 
1st  volume  of  Robison's  '  System  of 
Mechanical  Philosophy '  ( Edinburgh, 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW    OF    NATURE.        359 

the  book  was  almost  completely  forgotten  on  the  Con- 
tinent.1 No  real  progress  has  indeed  been  made  in  the 
explanation  of  physical  phenomena  by  the  application  of 


1822).  His  '  Elements  of  Mechani- 
cal Philosophy'  (Edinb.,  1804)  be- 
tray, according  to  Dugald  Stewart, 
"  a  strong  and  avowed  leaning  to 
the  theory  of  Boscovich"  (Works 
by  Hamilton,  vol.  v.  p.  107).  The 
theory  probably  found  favour, 
among  other  reasons,  because  it 
seemed  to  give  support  to  the  pre- 
valent corpuscular  theory  of  light, 
which  Euler  opposed,  as  he  did 
simple  action  at  a  distance.  In 
the  Scotch  school  of  philosophy, 
of  which  Dugald  Stewart  was  the 
most  popular  exponent,  Boscovich 
was  well  known.  Stewart  refers  to 
him  frequently  (Works by  Hamilton, 
vol.  ii.  pp.  50,  107,  110,  343  ;  vol. 
iii.  p.  233  ;  vol.  v.  p.  93  sqq.  ;  vol. 
vii.  p.  173  sqq.)  He  quotes  Priest- 
ley, Robison,  and  James  Hutton  as 
followers  of  Boscovich,  whilst  his 
own  adherence  is  certainly  very 
qualified,  and  he  makes  a  very 
pertinent  remark  in  his  Introduc- 
tion to  the  '  Elements  of  the  Philo- 
sophy of  the  Human  Mind '  (1792) : 
"I  cannot  help  taking  this  oppor- 
tunity of  remarking  that  if  physical 
inquirers  should  think  of  again  em- 
ploying themselves  in  speculations 
about  the  nature  of  matter,  instead 
of  attempting  to  ascertain  its  sen- 
sible properties  and  laws  (and  of 
late  there  seems  to  be  such  a  ten- 
dency among  some  of  the  followers 
of  Boscovich),  they  will  soon  involve 
themselves  in  an  inextricable  laby- 
rinth, and  the  first  principles  of 
physics  will  be  rendered  as  mys- 
terious and  chimerical  as  the  pneu- 
matology  of  the  schoolmen  "  (vol. 
ii.  p.  50).  Boscovich  seems  to  have 
been  fond  of  tracing  mathematical 
curves  to  represent  all  kinds  of  pro- 
cesses, such  as  the  intellectual  ad- 
vancement of  the  age,  and  he  shows 


graphically  that  this  was  declining 
(Dugald  Stewart's  quotation  in  his 
'Dissertation, 'Works,  vol.  i.  p.  499). 
1  When  Fechner  published  the 
first  edition  of  his  '  Atomenlehre ' 
(lsted.,Leipzig,1855;2nded.,1864), 
he  does  not  seem  to  have  known  of 
Boscovich's  treatise  (see  p.  229  of 
the  2nd  edition),  and  it  was  simi- 
larly unknown  to  the  Dutch  meteor- 
ologist Buys  Ballot,  whose  curves 
of  the  attracting  and  repelling 
forces  of  matter  agree  almost  ex- 
actly with  those  of  Boscovich  (see 
'  Fo'rtschritte  der  Physik,'  1849.  p. 
1  sqq.;  also  Rosenberger's  'Ge- 
schichte  der  Physik,'  vol.  iii.  p.  536 
sqq. )  In  French  scientific  literature 
the  treatise  of  Boscovich  is  mostly  ig- 
nored— the  '  Grande  Encyclopedic ' 
does  not  even  give  its  title.  In 
fact,  French  science  does  not  con- 
sider itself  beholden  to  the  cele- 
brated Jesuit  for  what  I  call  the 
astronomical  view  of  matter.  See 
St  Venant  in  '  Comptes  Rendus,' 
vol.  82,  p.  1223:  "  Plusieurs  auteurs, 
soit  anglais,  soit  allemands,  dans 
ses  ccuvres  qui  sont  du  reste  d'une 
haute  portee,  .  .  .  se  sont  pris  a. 
condamner  vivement,  sous  le  nom  de 
thtorie  de  Boscovich,  non  pas  son 
ideecapitale  de  reduction  des  atonies 
a  des  centres  d'action  de  forces, 
mais  la  loi  m£me,  la  loi  physique 
generale  des  actions  fouctious  des 
distances  niutuelles  des  particules 
qui  les  exercent  reciproquement  les 
unes  sur  les  autres.  Et  ils  attri- 
buent  ainsi  au  ce"lebre  religieux 
Verreur  grave  ou  sont  tomWs,  sui- 
vant  eux,  Navier,  Poisson  et  nos 
autres  savants,  createurs,  il  y  a  un 
demi-siecle,  de  la  me"canique  mole- 
culaire  ou  interne.  Or  cette  loi 
blnmee,  cette  loi  qui  a  etd,  raise  en 
a-uvre  aussi  par  Laplace,  &c. ,  et 


360  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

Boscovich's  or  similar  formulae,  though  the  idea  of  action 
at  a  distance  between  the  minute  particles  of  matter  un- 
derlies the  theories  by  which  Poisson,  Navier,  Cauchy, 
Lame",  and  others  calculated  the  effect  of  elastic  forces  in 
solid  bodies,  or  the  phenomena  of  light  passing  through 
transparent  and  crystalline  substances.  A  different  school 
of  physicists,  starting  from  ideas  of  a  different  kind,  with 
which  we  shall  become  acquainted  hereafter,  have  shown 
that  specific  notions  as  to  the  molecular  structure  of  bodies 
are  not  required  in  order  to  deal  with  the  phenomena 
referred  to.  Nevertheless,  the  idea  of  action  at  a  distance 
governing  the  movements  of  immeasurably  small,  as  it 
seemingly  does  those  of  immeasurably  large  masses  in 
nature,  received  a  great  support  by  the  development  of 
two  other  branches  of  science,  which  belong  essentially  to 
the  history  of  the  present  century. 
34.  The  sciences  of  electricity  and  magnetism  can  be  said 

Coulomb's  _       ,  , 

measure-       to   have   originated    with    Coulombs    accurate   measure- 
ments. 

ments  with  the  torsion -balance.  With  this  instrument 
he  measured  the  attracting  and  repelling  forces  of 
bodies,  electrified  or  magnetised,  by  comparing  them 
with  the  mechanical  forces  required  to  twist  a  metallic 
wire.  In  this  way  he  fixed  what  have  ever  since  his 
time  been  termed  the  units  of  electricity  or  magnetism, 
reducing  these  quantities  to  the  same  system  of  measure- 
ment with  which  we  measure  the  masses  or  inertia  of 
Extended  by  moving  bodies.  His  methods  were  adopted  and  niodi- 
weber!"1  fied  and  greatly  perfected  by  Gauss  and  Weber — the 

prise  par  Coriolis  et  Poncelet  pour    I   ment  dans  son   grand  et  principal 
base    de    la    mecanique    physique,       ouvrage,  mais  dan*  le  scholie  gen- 


n'est  autre  que  celle  de  Newton  lui- 
meme,  comme  on  le  voit  non  seule- 


eral   de  sa  non    moins   immortelle 
'  Optique.;" 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.         361 


former  applying  them  to  the  measurement  of  the  mag- 
netic forces  of  the  earth,  the  latter  to  that  of  the  forces 
exerted  by  currents  of  electricity — i.e.,  by  electricity 
which  is  not  at  rest  but  in  motion.  As  I  have  already 
stated,  the  measurements  of  Coulomb  confirmed  the 
prevalent  notion  that  action  at  a  distance,  varying 
inversely  as  the  square  of  the  distance,  and  directly  in 
the  proportion  of  the  quantities  of  the  acting  substance, 
was  a  universal  formula  or  law  of  nature.1  The  idea 


1  Coulomb's  exact  measurements 
of  the  attraction  and  repulsion  at  a 
distance  of  electrified  bodies  and  of 
magnets  were  published  during  the 
years  1784  to  1789  in  seven  memoirs 
presented  to  the  Paris  Academy  of 
Sciences.  They  are  conveniently 
collected,  together  with  some  other 
memoirs  of  Coulomb,  Poisson,  and 
others  on  kindred  subjects,  in  the 
first  volume  of  the  '  Collection  de 
Memoires  relatifs  a  la  Physique,' 
published  in  1884  by  the  Societe 
francaise  de  Physique.  Coulomb 
made  use  of  the  torsion-balance 
and  the  proof-plane,  the  actions  of 
which  he  carefully  examined.  He 
confirmed  the  law,  which  had  been 
vaguely  or  approximately  expressed 
by  various  writers  before  him,  that 
electrified  bodies  act  on  each  other 
with  a  force  which  is  proportional 
to  the  inverse  square  of  their  dis- 
tances. This  he  did  by  direct 
measurements  of  the  repulsion  of 
small  electrified  bodies  in  the  tor- 
sion-balance (1785,  1st  Memoire). 
He  then  extended  his  measure- 
ments by  an  indirect  method  to 
the  action  of  electrified  bodies  of 
larger  size  and  to  magnets  (2nd 
Memoire).  He  also  defined  what 
is  meant  by  quantity  and  density 
of  electricity  and  magnetism,  and 
showed  how  these  could  be  meas- 
ured and  how  the  action  of  elec- 
trified bodies  and  magnets  depended 


on  the  more  or  less  of  these  quan- 
tities. Coulomb's  researches  con- 
tain experiments  of  great  delicacy. 
Although  the  laws  which  bear  his 
name  appear  so  simple  when  written 
down,  the  phenomena  they  repre- 
sent are  most  complicated,  as  in 
the  case  of  electricity  the  effect  of 
electrical  influence,  called  by  Fara- 
day induction,  and  in  the  case  of 
magnetism  the  presence  of  the 
earth's  magnetism,  and  the  fact 
that  we  have  never  to  do  with  one 
kind  of  magnetism  but  always  with 
two  states,  destroys  all  chance  of  ex- 
hibiting experimentally  the  simple 
case  represented  by  the  mathemati- 
cal formula.  It  was  therefore  ne- 
cessary to  consider  this  formula  as 
being  merely  a  convenient  descrip- 
tion of  the  elementary  action  of 
supposed  isolated  quantities  of 
electricity  and  magnetism,  and  by 
a  process  of  summation  to  deduce 
mathematically  the  actual  effects 
for  such  cases  of  interaction  as 
are  actually  observable  in  the  la- 
boratory. It  was  especially  the 
phenomena  of  the  distribution  of 
electricity  on  the  surface  of  elec- 
trified bodies  of  simple  shape  and 
the  distribution  of  magnetic  forces 
in  the  neighbourhood  of  magnets 
which  had  to  be  calculated  and 
measured.  In  physical  astronomy 
a  similar  course  of  reasoning  and 
observation  combined  had  verified 


362 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


of  mass,  which  in  the  Newtonian  formula  meant  merely 
the  quantity  of  matter,  had  indeed  to  be  enlarged,  and 
to  the  attracting  forces  had  to  be  added  those  of  re- 
pulsion ;  still,  though  physically  the  phenomena  were 
entirely  different,  the  mathematical  expression  which 
ruled  the  two  electric  and  the  two  magnetic  quantities, 
usually  termed  fluids,  looked  very  much  like  the  New- 
tonian gravitation  formula :  it  betrayed  philosophers  into 
thinking  they  possessed  an  explanation  where  really  they 
had  only  a  measurement  and  a  description.1 


Newton's  elementary  law  of  gravita- 
tion, Laplace  as  it  were  summing 
up  the  evidence  in  his  great  work. 
What  Laplace  did  for  Newton  was 
done  by  Poisson  for  Coulomb's  ele- 
mentary law  of  electric  and  mag- 
netic action,  and  on  a  still  larger 
scale  by  Gauss,  who  worked  out 
the  mathematical  theory  and  ap- 
plied it  to  the  case  of  the  magnetic 
distribution  on  the  earth's  sur- 
face. In  England,  already  before 
Coulomb's  researches  were  pub- 
lished, Cavendish  had,  likewise  by 
a  combination  of  experiment  and 
calculation,  established  the  elemen- 
tary formulae  and  properties  of 
electrical  phenomena.  See  note  to 
the  following  page. 

1  The  exact  measurements  of 
Coulomb  and  the  mathematical 
analysis  of  Poissou  and  Gauss 
superseded  the  vaguer  discussions 
on  the  nature  of  electricity  and 
magnetism  which  were  very  fre- 
quent before  that  period,  just  as 
the  mathematical  principles  of 
Newton  and  Laplace  drove  into 
the  background  the  discussion  on 
the  nature  and  cause  of  gravity. 
Coulomb  himself  does  not  profess 
to  settle  the  controversy  carried  on 
between  the  two  schools  of  which 
Dufay  and  Franklin  can  be  con- 
sidered as  the  principal  representa- 


tives— viz.,  whether  there  existed 
two  electric  fluids  or  only  one. 
Coulomb  judged  the  rival  views, 
simply  as  to  their  usefulness  in 
describing  and  measuring  phenom- 
ena :  "  Comme  ces  deux  explications 
n'ont  qu'un  degr^  de  probabilite 
plus  ou  nioins  grand  je  previens, 
pour  mettre  la  theorie  ...  a, 
I'abri  de  toute  dispute  systematique, 
que  dans  la  supposition  des  deux, 
fluides  electriques  je  n'ai  d'autre 
intention  que  de  presenter  avec  le 
moins  d'elements  possibles,  les  re"- 
sultats  du  calcul  et  de  1'experience, 
et  non  d'indiquer  les  veYitables 
causes  de  1'electricite  "  ('Collection 
de  Memoires,'  vol.  i.  p.  252).  He 
had  previously,  in  1777,  rejected 
the  theory  of  vortices  to  explain 
magnetic  phenomena  :  "  II  semble 
qu'il  resulte  de  1'experience  que  ce 
ne  sont  point  des  tourbillons  qui 
produisent  les  differents  phe'nom- 
enes  aimantains,  et  que,  pour  les 
expliquer,  il  faut  udcessairement 
recourir  a,  des  forces  attractives  et 
re'pulsives  de  la  nature  de  celles, 
dont  on  est  oblige  de  se  servir  pour 
expliquer  la  pesanteur  des  corps  et 
la  physique  celeste "  (vol.  i.  p.  8). 
And  in  1789  he  is  still  more 
cautious  :  "  Pour  eviter  toute  dis- 
cussion, j'avertis  .  .  .  que  toute 
hypothese  d'attraction  et  de  rdpul- 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        363 

The  extension  and  confirmation  which  the  Newtonian 
attraction  formula  had  thus  gained  in  the  minds  of 
many  seemed  to  be  entirely  upset  by  a  series  of  dis- 
coveries in  which  electrical,  and  subsequently  magnetic, 
phenomena  played  an  important  part.  These  were,  the 
discovery  of  galvanic  electricity  by  Galvani  in  1791  and 
by  Volta  in  1800  ;  of  the  physiological  and  chemical 
effects  of  this  form  of  electricity,  especially  by  Davy 
(1806);  of  the  magnetic  effect  of  moving  electricity  by 
Oersted  in  1820;  of  the  connection  of  heat  and  elec- 
tricity by  Seebeck  in  1822  ;  of  induction  by  Faraday  in 
1831— i.e.,  of  the  action  of  electric  currents  and  magnets 
in  generating  other  electric  currents  or  magnetic  effects 
in  bodies  which  are  moving  in  their  neighbourhood ;  and, 
finally,  of  diamagnetism  by  Faraday  in  1845. 

Many  of  the  celebrated  men  with  whose  names  the  mod-        se. 

Davy  and 

ern  discoveries  in  electricity  are  identified,  and  amongst  Faraday, 
them  notably  Davy  and  Faraday,  were  not  brought  up 
in  the  mathematical  school  of  the  Continent,1  in  which 

sion  suivant  une  loi  quelconque  ne   |    humous    papers    (edited    by   Max- 
doit  etre  regardee  que  comme  une       well    in    1879    under    the    title    of 
forrnule    qui    exprime    un    resultat 
d'experience  "  (vol.  i.  p.  297). 


1  To  these  must  be  added  the 
name  of  Cavendish  (1731-1810), 
whose  electrical  researches,  in 
which  he  anticipated  many  of  Cou- 
lomb's results,  proceeded  on  en- 


'  The  Electrical  Researches  of  the 
Hon.  Henry  Cavendish')  he  anti- 
cipated, as  Maxwell  has  shown, 
many  later  investigations  of  British 
and  Continental  writers.  He  had 
a  clear  notion  of  electrical  capacity, 
of  potential  and  of  electrical  resist- 


tirely  different  lines  from  those  of      ance,  he  anticipated  Ohm's  law — 


the  Continental  school.  He  proved 
— in  or  before  1773 — from  the  fact 
that  a  small  globe  situated  in  the 


i.e.,  the  proportionality  between 
the  electro-motive  force  and  the 
current  in  the  same  conductor. 


hollow  of  a  large  electrified  globe  |  He  studied  the  properties  of  diel- 
and  communicating  with  it  showed  I  ectrics,  and  "not  only  anticipated 
no  signs  of  electricity,  that  electric  !  Faraday's  discovery  of  the  specific 
attraction  and  repulsion  must  be  |  inductive  capacity  of  different  sub- 
inversely  as  the  square  of  the  dis-  stances,  but  measured  its  numer- 
tance.  In  his  published  and  post-  ical  value  in  several  substances  " 


364 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


the  astronomical  view  of  phenomena  had  been  established 
and  strengthened  mainly  by  a  development  of  the  New- 
tonian philosophy.  They  belonged  to  another  school, 
which  approached  that  great  field  of  research  from  the 
purely  experimental  side, — mainly,  so  far  as  Davy  was 
concerned,  from  the  side  of  chemistry,  which,  dealing 
with  the  qualitative,  not  merely  the  quantitative,  proper- 
ties of  matter,  was  at  that  period  almost  entirely  thrown 


(Maxwell's  Introduction  to  the 
'  Researches,'  p.  xlix  sqq.)  Caven- 
dish's electrical  work  seems  to  have 
remained  unnoticed  abroad.  Cu- 
vier,  who  fully  appreciates  him  as 
a  pioneer  in  modern  chemistry, 
does  not  refer  to  his  electrical 
researches,  and  in  Continental 
works  his  name  is  hardly  men- 
tioned in  connection  with  elec- 
trical science.  He,  however,  clearly 
belongs  to  the  same  lineage  as 
Davy  and  Faraday,  whose  breadth 
of  experimental  observation  some- 
what prevented  them  from  fully 
assimilating  the  results  of  Coulomb 
and  his  school,  which  moved  in 
narrower  but  more  precise  lines. 
If  Cavendish  was  unknown  abroad 
as  an  electrician,  Coulomb  was 
little  known  in  England.  Whewell, 
who  did  more  than  any  other  to 
make  known  the  researches  of  the 
mathematical  school  (see  his  article 
in  the  '  Encyclopaedia  Metropoli- 
tana,'  1826,  and  his  British  Associ- 
ation Report,  1835),  could  state  in 
the  first  edition  of  his  '  History  of 
the  Inductive  Sciences'  (1837)  that 
"  the  reception  of  the  Coulombian 
theory  has  hitherto  not  been  so 
general  as  might  have  been  reason- 
ably expected  from  its  very  beauti- 
ful accordance  with  the  facts  which 
it  contemplates"  (3rd  ed.,  vol.  iii. 
p.  28).  He  then  refers  to  the  ex- 
periments of  Snow  Harris.  These 
experiments,  as  well  as  those  of 


Faraday,  carried  on  about  the  same 
time,  dealt  largely  with  the  proper- 
ties of  dielectrics  and  of  what  we 
now  call  the  electric  field,  a  subject 
almost  entirely  neglected  by  the 
mathematical  school  of  that  period. 
It  was  not  till  1845  that  William 
Thomson  (Lord "Kelvin)  cleared  up 
the  whole  subject  in  a  memoir, 
"On  the  Mathematical  theory  of 
Electricity  in  Equilibrium "  (see 
'Reprint  of  Papers..'  &c.,  p.  15). 
He  there  refers  to  the  fact  that 
"many  have  believed  Coulomb's 
theory  to  be  overturned  by  the  in- 
vestigations "  of  Snow  Harris  and 
Faraday,  and  he  therefore  pro- 
poses to  show  that  "all  the  experi- 
ments which  they  have  made  hav- 
ing direct  reference  to  the  distri- 
bution of  electricity  in  equilibrium 
are  in  full  accordance  with  the 
laws  of  Coulomb,  and  must  there- 
fore be  considered  as  confirming 
the  theory"  (p.  18).  He  thus 
brought  together  the  two  inde- 
pendent lines  of  research  and 
thought,  the  mathematical  and  the 
experimental,  represented  by  the 
school  of  Gauss  and  Weber  abroad, 
and  by  Faraday  in  England,  and 
suggested  those  further  researches 
of  which  Maxwell's  '  Treatise  on 
Electricity  and  Magnetism '  is  the 
great  exponent.  See  the  preface 
to  this  work,  p.  xi,  &c.,  1873  ;  also 
Maxwell's  '  Scientific  Papers,'  vol. 
ii.  pp.  258,  302,  304. 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF   NATURE.        365 

upon  experimental  research.1  Chemistry  had  only  just 
entered  the  list  of  the  exact  sciences,  by  the  use  of  the 
balance,  largely  owing  to  Lavoisier  and  his  followers. 


1  Although  Faraday's  '  Experi-  , 
mental  Researches  in  Electricity' 
(1831-52)  contain  mostly  what 
chemists  would  call  "qualitative" 
investigations  and  only  few  exact 
"quantitative"  measurements  — 
forming  in  this  respect  a  very 
remarkable  contrast  to  Weber's 
'  Electrodynamische  Maasbestim- 
mungen  '  (1846-78) — it  is  important 
to  remark  that  one  of  the  methods 
for  exact  measurement  of  the 
electric  current — viz.,  by  the  chem- 
ical decomposition  of  compounds 
— was  established  by  Faraday  in 
1833  and  1834.  He  showed  that 
whenever  decomposition  took  place 
the  quantities  decomposed  were  in 
proportion  to  the  amount  of  elec- 
tricity flowing  through  the  circuit 
and  in  proportion  to  the  chemical 
equivalents.  Owing  to  the  want  of 
a  clear  definition  of  quantity  and 
intensity  of  current,  Berzelius  op- 
posed this  view  of  Faraday's  as 
illogical,  confounding  the  quan- 
tity of  substance  decomposed  with 
the  force  required  to  set  it  free. 
Clearer  definitions  and  accumu- 
lated experience  have  confirmed 
Faraday's  law,  which  is  now 
looked  upon  as  one  of  the  best  es- 
tablished general  facts  of  chemical 
and  electrical  science.  Somewhat 
earlier  than  Faraday,  Georg  Simon 
Ohm  established  (1827,  'Die  gal- 
vanische  Kette,  mathernatisch 
bearbeitet ')  the  proportionality  of 
the  quantity  of  electricity  passing 
through  a  circuit  with  the  electro- 
motive force  in  the  same  conductor, 
introduced  the  notion  of  electrical 
resistance,  and  showed  how  this 
varies  as  the  length  and  inversely  as 
the  thickness  of  the  same  conductor, 
and  is  different  in  different  con- 
ductors. The  accuracy  of  Ohm's 


law,  though  elaborately  tested  by 
Fechner  and  confirmed  by  Pouillet, 
was  frequently  doubted  ;  in  France 
it  met  with  tardy  recognition,  and 
in  England  some  of  the  most  im- 
portant researches — such  as  those  of 
Faraday — were  carried  on  without 
reference  to  it.  In  the  first  edition 
of  Whe well's  History  it  is  not  men- 
tioned. When  the  second  edition 
was  published  (1847),  Ohm  had 
received  the  Copley  Medal  of 
the  Royal  Society  (1841),  and 
Wheatstone  had  besides  in  the  year 
1843  drawn  attention  to  the  clear 
definitions  which  Ohm  had  intro- 
duced. The  opinion  has  been  ex- 
pressed that  Ohm  found  his  law  by 
theoretical  considerations  based  on 
analogy  with  the  flow  of  heat  in 
conductors,  and  that  he  subse- 
quently proved  it  experimentally. 
The  publication  of  Ohm's  collected 
papers  by  Lommel  ('Gesammelte 
Abhandlungen,'  Leipzig,  1892),  how- 
ever, disproves  this  opinion  ;  as  his 
experimental  measurements  had 
during  1825  and  1826— not  without 
some  initial  mistakes — led  him  to 
the  well-known  expression  of  the 
relations  of  the  different  quantities 
(see  LommeFs  Introduction,  p.  vii). 
Whereas  in  Germany  it  was  a  pure- 
ly scientific  interest — that,  namely, 
of  subjecting  physical  phenomena. 
to  mathematical  calculation — which 
induced  Ohm,  Gauss,  and  Weber 
to  devise  instruments  and  methods 
for  exact  measurement,  it  was  in 
England  mainly  the  practical  re- 
quirements of  telegraphy  which 
created  the  desire  for  clear  defini- 
tions and  exact  methods.  With 
these  requirements  in  view  Wheat- 
stone  invented  his  instruments  and 
drew  attention  to  the  definitions  of 
Ohm.  See  his  Bakeriau  Lecture  for 


366 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


Yet  the  great  variety,  more  than  the  exact  measurement 
of  phenomena,  attracted  the  attention  of  natural  philoso- 
phers in  this  new  field.  And  when  through  Davy,Berzelius, 
and  Faraday  in  different  ways  the  importance  of  electric 
action  in  chemical  processes  became  established,  it  was 
natural  that  from  this  school  an  entirely  different  view  of 
electrical  and  magnetic  phenomena  should  emanate :  we 
may  term  it — in  opposition  to  the  astronomical — the  phys- 
ical view  of  phenomena.  This  view,  which,  as  the  astron- 
omical view  had  done,  found  later  on  its  expression  in  a 
mathematical  formula,  will  occupy  our  attention  in  a  sub- 
sequent chapter.  It  has  in  the  course  of  the  second  half 
of  the  century  very  largely  expelled  the  other  and.  rival 
view  from  the  domain  of  molar  and  molecular  physics. 
But  the  astronomical  view,  with  its  largely  developed 
mathematical  apparatus,  was  not  easily  defeated :  it  was 
37.  quite  able  to  grapple  with  even  such  complicated  processes 

Ampere  and 

Weber  de-     as  the  discoveries  of  Oersted  and  Faraday  had  revealed. 

velop  the 

In  the  opinion  of  many  Continental  thinkers  it  won  its 
greatest  laurels  when,  under  the  treatment  of  Ampere  in 
France  and  of  Neumann  and  Weber  in  Germany,  the 
perplexing  interactions  of  magnets,  diamagnets,  and 


astronomi- 


1843  (' Phflos.  Transactions,' 1843, 
p.  303,  &c.) :  "An  energetic  source 
of  light,  of  heat,  of  chemical  action, 
and  of  mechanical  power,  we  only 
require  to  know  the  conditions  un- 
der which  its  various  effects  may 
be  most  economically  and  ener- 
getically manifested  to  enable  us 
to  determine  whether  the  high  ex- 
pectations formed  in  many  quarters 
of  some  of  these  applications  are 
founded  on  reasonable  hope  or  on 
fallacious  conjecture. "  Forty  years 
later  Lord  Kelvin,  in  his  address 


"  On  the  Electrical  Units  of  Meas- 
urement "  (1883 ;  see  '  Popular 
Lectures  and  Addresses,'  voL  L  p. 
76),  could  still  speak  of  the  com- 
paratively recent  date  at  which 
"anything  that  could  be  called 
electric  measurement  had  come  to 
be  regularly  practised  in  most  of  the 
scientific  laboratories  of  the  world," 
whereas  such  measurements  had 
then  been  for  many  years  "  familiar 
to  the  electricians  of  the  submarine 
cable  factories  and  testing  sta- 
tions." 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        367 


electric  circuits — the  phenomena  of  electro-magnetism, 
diamagnetism,  and  induction — were  all  resolved  into 
elementary  processes  of  attraction  and  repulsion,  and 
summed  up  in  a  formula  which  looked  like  an  extension 
of  the  Newtonian  gravitation  formula,  revealing  the 
mysterious  influence  of  molecular  forces. 

"  Oersted  had  found  that  an  electric  current  acts  on  a 
magnetic  pole,  but  that  it  neither  attracts  it  nor  repels  it, 
but  causes  it  to  move  round  the  current.  He  expressed 
this  by  saying  that  the  electric  conflict  acts  in  a  revolving 
manner.  The  most  obvious  deduction  from  this  new  fact 
was,  that  the  action  of  the  current  on  the  magnet  is  not 
a  push-and-pull  force,  but  a  rotary  force,  and  accordingly 
many  minds  began  to  speculate  on  vortices  and  streams 
of  ether,  whirling  round  the  current.  But  Ampere,  by  a 
combination  of  mathematical  skill  and  experimental  in- 
genuity, first  proved  that  two  electric  currents  act  on  one 
another,  and  then  analysed  this  action  into  the  resultant 
of  a  system  of  push-and-pull  forces  between  the  elemen- 
tary parts  of  these  currents."1 

Weber  in  Germany  took  up  the  work  where  Ampere 
had  left  it.2  One  of  his  objects  was  to  combine  the 


1  Clerk  Maxwell  "  On  Action  at 
a    Distance"    ('Scientific    Papers,' 
vol.  ii.  p.  317). 

2  Weber's  interest  was  twofold. 
The    primary    object    was    to    put 
accurate  quantitative  data   in   the 
place  of  merely  qualitative  descrip- 
tions or  mere  estimates  of  pheno- 
mena.    He  had  then  already  pub- 
lished, together  with  his  brothers 
(see   supra,  p.    196,    note   3),    two 
works  in  which  in  a  similar   way 
exact  research  has  taken  the  place 
of   inexact   description.     The   first 


was  his  experimental  investigation 
of  wave-motion  ('  Die  Wellenlehre 
auf  Experiments  gegriindet,'  1825), 
the  other  the  still  more  delicate  at- 
tempt to  treat  a  physiological  pheno- 
menon, the  mechanism  of  the  organs 
of  locomotion,  on  exact  mechanical 
principles  (1836).  This  rare  gift  of 
exactness,  invaluable  at  all  times, 
but  almost  unique  at  that  time  in 
Germany,  where  philosophical  vague- 
ness was  only  too  common,  attract- 
ed the  notice  of  Gauss,  who  brought 
Weber  to  Gottingeu  in  1830  after 


368  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

different  electric  phenomena — those  of  electricity  in  the 
state  of  rest,  called  statical  effects ;  those  of  electric 
currents  on  each  other,  the  dynamical  results ;  and  those 
of  electric  conductors  in  a  state  of  motion,  the  pheno- 
mena of  induction — in  one  general  and  fundamental 
formula  or  law.  He  had  before  him  Coulomb's  electro- 
static formula,  Ampere's  electro- dynamic  formula,  and  a 
more  general  one  established  by  Franz  Neumann,  which 
described  and  embraced  not  only  the  phenomena  dis- 
covered by  Oersted,  but  also  those  of  moving  conductors 
discovered  by  Faraday.  It  is  not  necessary  here  to  enter 
into  the  details  of  the  investigations,  experimental  and 
mathematical,  by  the  aid  of  which  Weber  succeeded  in 
establishing  his  very  remarkable  and  seemingly  all- 
embracing  formula.  Two  remarks,  however,  present 
themselves,  bearing  upon  the  history  of  thought  and  the 
value  of  precise  mathematical  expressions.  The  first  is, 
that  as  the  gravitation  formula  necessitated  a  series  of 
the  most  careful  definitions  and  measurements  of  physical 
ss.  quantities,  and  the  invention  of  accurate  instruments  and 

Weber's  fun- 
damental     methods  or  measurement,  so  the  first  and  probably  the 

measure- 
ments,        most  valuable  performances  of  Weber  were  his  ingenious 

apparatus,  and  the  careful  measurements  by  which  he 

the  death  of  Tobias  Mayer.  Gauss  bestimmungen '  of  the  endeavour  to 
introduced  Weber  to  his  own  exact  i  determine  natural  phenomena  ac- 
measurements  of  terrestrial  magnet-  cording  to  number  and  measure, 
ism,  and  from  hence  Weber's  own  expressing  surprise  that  this  has 
line  of  thought  led  through  the  not  yet  been  done  in  electro- 
phenomena  of  magneto  -  induction  dynamics,  and  then  proceeds  to  de- 
(discovered  by  Faraday  in  1831)  .  scribe  his  "electro-dynamometer," 
and  terrestrial  magneto -induction  an  instrument  used  by  him  for 
(1832)  to  electro  -  dynamics,  the  ;  many  years.  With  this  instrument 
science  which  Ampere  had  created  he  then,  further,  proceeds  to  con- 
in  the  years  1820  to  1823.  In  1846  firm  Ampere's  formula  for  the  action 
Weber  speaks  in  the  introduction  ;  at  a  distance  of  the  elements  of 
to  the  '  Electro-dynamische  Maas-  electric  currents. 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        369 


fixed  the  elementary  conceptions  and  quantities  with 
which  he  operated.  All  his  researches  were  comprised 
under  the  very  significant  title  "  electro-dynamical  mea- 
surements." As  such  they  remain  a  great  monument 
of  ingenuity  and  unparalleled  accuracy.1  The  second 


1  Gauss  had,  some  years  before 
Weber  commenced  his  electrical  re- 
searches, introduced  the  idea  of  an 
absolute  measure  of  other  than 
mechanical  forces  —  i.e.,  following 
up  the  definition  of  force  in  the 
Newtonian  laws  of  motion,  that  it 
is  the  cause  which  brings  about  a 
change  of  motion,  he  suggested  that 
every  physical  force  can  be  measured 
by  the  velocity  it  imparts  to  a  mov- 
able body  of  measurable  mass,  the 
quantity  of  mass  being  in  the  same 
locality  measured  by  its  weight ; 
and  he  applied  this  to  the  measure- 
ment of  magnetic  forces.  In  ap- 
plying the  same  idea  to  the  measure- 
ment of  electric  currents,  Weber 
came  at  once  upon  the  circumstance 
that  the  forces  exerted  by  an  elec- 
tric current  can  be  measured  in 
two  ways — viz.,  by  the  action  they 
have  upon  magnets  or  by  that 
which  they  have  on  other  electric 
currents.  Now  by  a  familiar  con- 
ception, electricians  look  upon  a 
current  of  electricity  as  measur- 
able by  the  quantity  of  electric- 
ity which  flows  through  a  section 
of  the  circuit  in  a  given  unit  of 
time,  this  quantity  of  electricity 
being  measurable  in  the  same  way 
as  Coulomb  measured  the  action 
at  a  distance  of  charged  bodies. 
Should  it  then  be  possible  to 
carry  out  this  latter  measurement 
of  an  electric  current,  a  comparison 
between  the  electro-magnetic  and 
the  known  electro-static  units  of 
electricity  would  become  possible. 
Faraday  had  already,  in  1833  and 
1834,  made  estimates  of  the  numer- 
ical relation  of  the  quantity  of 
electricity  in  a  current,  measured 

VOL.  I. 


by  its  chemical  or  electro-magnetic 
effects,  and  of  the  same  quantity  if 
produced  by  an  electrical  machine. 
These  estimates  were  more  than 
twenty  years  later,  in  1856,  reduced 
to  accurate  measurements  by  Weber 
and  Kohlrausch.  Through  these 
measurements,  which  confirmed  the 
enormous  numbers  which  are  re- 
vealed when  we  compare  electricity 
at  rest  and  electricity  in  motion, 
Weber  finished  the  series  of  ac- 
curate measurements,  reduced  to 
an  absolute  or  mechanical  standard, 
which  had  been  begun  by  Gauss  in 
1833.  It  was  soon  recognised  of 
what  practical  importance  these 
data  must  be  to  electricians.  Ac- 
cordingly the  British  Association  at 
their  meeting  at  Manchester  in  1861 
appointed  a  committee,  on  the  sug- 
gestion and  under  the  presidency 
of  Sir  William  Thomson,  called  the 
"  British  Association  Committee  of 
Electrical  Standards."  "This  com- 
mittee worked  for  nearly  ten  years 
through  the  whole  field  of  electro- 
magnetic and  electro-static  measure- 
ment, until  in  its  final  report,  pre- 
sented to  the  Exeter  meeting  in 
August  1869,  it  fairly  launched  the 
absolute  system  for  general  use" 
(Thomson,  '  Popular  Lectures  and 
Addresses,'  vol.  i.  p.  84).  In  recog- 
nition of  Weber's  great  merit  in 
first  introducing  this  system  into 
electrical  science  and  practice,  the 
name  "  Weber "  had  been  selected 
by  Latimer  Clark  for  the  unit  of 
current.  In  the  final  fixing  of  the 
units  in  Paris  in  1881  other  units 
than  those  previously  in  use  were 
adopted,  and  to  avoid  confusion  the 
names  were  somewhat  differently 

2A 


370 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


point  I  wish  to  urge  is,  how  in  those  clays  the  Newtonian 
formula  was  taken  as  the  great  model  of  a  law  of  nature, 
and  how  the  researches  of  Coulomb,  Poisson,  Ampere,  and 
Weber  stand  in  logical  connection  with  the  theory  of 
gravitation.  Let  us  see  what  Weber  himself  says  on  this 
subject : l  "  After  the  general  laws  of  motion  had  fur- 


chosen.  This  explains  the  fact, 
deplored  by  Weber's  friends  and 
admirers,  that  his  name  has  dropt 
out  of  the  list  of  terms  now  adopted 
throughout  the  civilised  world.  (See 
Wiedemann,  '  Die  Electricitat, ' 
Braunschweig,  1885,  vol.  iv.  p. 
906,  &c.)  Recently  Prof.  Lodge 
has  suggested  the  introduction  of 
the  names  of  Weber  and  Gauss  to 
denote  some  of  the  derived  units  in 
the  electrical  measurements.  See 
Brit.  Assoc.  Report,  1895,  p.  197  n. 
1  Weber's  theoretical  conception 
of  the  nature  of  electric  action  at  a 
distance  is  mixed  up  with  his  exact 
measurements  of  electrical  quanti- 
ties, though  these  can  be  stated 
without  making  use  of  his  theoreti- 
cal conceptions.  It  is  the  nature 
of  the  absolute  system  of  measure- 
ment that  it  establishes  numeri- 
cal relations  based  upon  a  small 
number  of  original  units  (space, 
time,  and  mass,  or  space  and  time 
alone,  see  note  to  p.  323  above) 
which  are  universally  intelligible. 
Whatever,  therefore,  the  theoretical 
views  may  be  which  led  the  investi- 
gation, in  the  end  these  are  elim- 
inated in  the  system  of  original 
(primary)  and  derived  (secondary) 
units.  But  Weber's  theory  com- 
mands attention  for  its  own  sake 
as  the  furthest  stage  to  which 
the  gravitational  view  of  phenom- 
ena, provisionally  introduced  by 
Newton,  has  been  pushed.  It  has 
been  extolled  and  condemned,  ac- 
cording to  the  favour  with  which 
the  purely  mathematical  treatment 
of  phenomena  has  been  received. 


In  the  school  of  Laplace  this  purely 
mathematical  treatment  quite  ob- 
scured all  other  views  which  did 
not  minister  to  it.  Thus  Laplace 
remained  to  the  end  an  adherent  of 
the  emission  or  corpuscular  theory 
of  light,  and  opposed  the  ideas  of 
Young  and  Fresnel,  who  developed 
the  dynamical  view.  In  order  to 
make  the  cosmical  view  of  nature 
useful  for  the  explanation  of  mole- 
cular phenomena,  two  distinct  and 
definite  conceptions,  contained  in 
the  gravitation  formula,  had  to  be 
modified  and  enlarged.  The  con- 
ception of  matter,  which  in  physical 
astronomy  is  limited  to  gravitational 
matter,  had  to  be  extended  so  as  to 
bring  into  calculation  what  was  then 
called  imponderable  matter,  such  as 
light,  heat,  and  electricity.  And 
the  law  of  gravitation,  which  defines 
the  purely  attractive  property  of 
ponderable  matter,  had  to  be  modi- 
fied so  as  to  embrace  also  the  repul- 
sive action  observable  in  a  certain 
class  of  phenomena.  Coulomb  had 
shown  that  ponderable  matter 
charged  with  electricity  followed 
the  same  formula  for  attraction 
and  repulsion  as  gravitating  bodies 
did  :  he  simply  adopted  the  two- 
fluid  theory  of  electric  matter. 
Poisson  developed  the  mathematics 
of  fluids,  actuated  byrepelling  forces 
depending  on  the  inverse  square  of 
the  distance.  Oersted  showed  the 
action  of  electric  currents  on  mag- 
nets ;  and  Ampere  showed  that 
magnets  can  in  their  action  be  sup- 
planted by  electric  currents.  La- 
place very  early  satisfied  himself  that 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF   NATURE.        371 


nished  a  foundation,  there  remained  in  physics  mainly  the 
investigation  of  the  laws  of  interaction  of  bodies ;  for 
without  interaction  bodies  would  for  ever  remain  in  that 
state  of  rest  or  motion  in  which  they  happened  to  be. 


these  actions  of  ponderable  matter, 
in  which  electricity  was  flowing, 
could  be  reduced  to  an  action  at  a 
distance  proportional  to  the  inverse 
square  of  the  elements  of  the  electric 
circuits.  When  Faraday  showed 
that  a  current  of  electricity  under 
certain  conditions  induced  in  con- 
ductors in  its  neighbourhood  other 
currents,  this  was  explained  by 
saying  that  the  electric  fluid  exerted 
not  only  pondero-motoric  but  also 
electro- motoric  action  at  a  distance. 
Not  only  did  electrified  matter  act 
on  other  electrified  matter,  but 
electricity  as  a  fluid  acted  on  elec- 
tricity itself.  Weber  adopted,  for 
the  purpose  of  putting  these  ap- 
parent actions  into  mathematical 
language,  and  for  finding  an  ele- 
mentary law  of  the  ultimate  par- 
ticles of  electric  matter  out  of 
which  by  summation  the  observ- 
able data  might  be  calculated,  the 
hypothesis  of  Fechner,  according  to 
which  in  an  electric  current  the 
two  electric  fluids  were  moving 
with  equal  velocity  in  opposite 
directions.  It  then  became  evident 
— looking  at  the  phenomena  dis- 
covered by  Oersted,  Ampere,  and 
Faraday — that  the  electro  -  static 
formula  of  Coulomb  required  to 
be  supplemented  by  an  additional 
term,  if  the  mutual  action  was  to 
be  determined  not  only  for  the  case 
of  equilibrium  and  rest,  but  also  for 
that  of  relative  motion.  The  ad- 
ditional term,  depending  on  this 
relative  motion,  had  to  be  found. 
(See  '  Electrodynamische  Maasbes- 
timmungen,'  vol.  i.  p.  102).  From 
this  starting-point,  and  with  this 
definite  problem  in  view,  Weber  un- 
dertook a  series  of  most  valuable 
measurements.  No  doubt  can  exist 


as  to  the  lasting  importance  of  these 
measurements.  Any  theoretical  con- 
ception which  produces  in  its  appli- 
cation such  results  must  hold  a 
prominent  place  in  the  history  of 
scientific  thought.  And  the  very 
fact  that,  unlike  Boscovich  and 
other  purely  metaphysical  theorists, 
Weber  undertook  to  fix  by  experi- 
ment the  actual  constants  or  nu- 
merical quantities  which  his  ab- 
stract formula  contained,  led  to 
much  enlargement  of  actual  know- 
ledge. I  will  mention  only  one 
of  the  most  interesting  points  in 
his  elaborate  researches.  I  stated 
above  that  it  took  a  whole  century 
after  the  discovery  of  the  law  of 
gravitation  before  the  gravitation 
constant  was  approximately  fixed, 
but  that  for  the  progress  of  phy- 
sical astronomy  this  was  of  little 
importance,  gravity  being  a  uni- 
versal property  of  matter.  Still 
such  a  constant  exists,  because  we 
possess  another  definition  of  matter 
— viz.,  inertia  or  mass.  The  con- 
stant in  Coulomb's  law  cannot  be 
determined  in  a  similar  manner,  as 
the  property  of  attraction  or  repul- 
sion defines  for  us  ultimately  the 
numerical  quantity  of  electricity. 
We  have — so  far — no  other  ultimate 
absolute  measure  of  electricity.  But 
in  Weber's  law  it  was  the  quantities 
of  electrical  matter  which  acted  on 
each  other  not  only  according  to 
their  distances,  but  also  according 
to  their  relative  motion  or  their 
velocities.  A  second  constant  thus 
entered  into  his  formula,  and  this 
constant  established  a  relation  be- 
tween electricity  at  rest  and  elec- 
tricity in  motion.  This  constant 
was  a  velocity,  and,  if  determinable, 
it  revealed  a  constant  of  nature  in 


372  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

All  changes  of  these  states,  and  all  phenomena  depen- 
dent thereon,  are  therefore  consequences  of  these  inter- 
actions. But  bodies  exert  such  mutual  actions  when  in 
contact  as  well  as  from  a  distance,  and  it  was  evident 
that  a  beginning  had  to  be  made  with  the  latter  in 
order  to  gain  a  clue  for  the  investigation  of  the  former ; 
this  being  especially  needful  whenever  the  spatial  rela- 
tions of  bodies  escape  observation,  as  is  the  case  with 
bodies  which  are  in  contact.  And  so  it  has  really 
happened,  inasmuch  as  a  beginning  was  made  by  ex- 
amining the  mutual  action  of  cosmic  bodies — i.e.,  with 
the  phenomena  of  gravitation.  To  this  first  field  of 
research — viz.,  the  phenomena  of  gravitation — there  was 
then  added  the  investigation  of  electric  and  magnetic 
interactions,  as  next  to  gravitation  these  are  the  only 
actions  which  take  place  from  one  body  to  another  at 
measurable  distances, — these  actions  being  themselves 
measurable.  Now  for  a  long  time  Xewton's  doctrine 
of  gravitation  furnished  the  leading  idea  for  nearly  all 
theories  of  electricity  and  magnetism,  till  a  new  clue 
was  gained  through  Oersted's  and  Ampere's  discoveries 

the   form   of   a  velocity.      It   had  tain  conditions  an  electrical  wave- 

for    Weber   a   theoretical    as    well  motion    might    take    place    in    an 

as  a  practical  meaning,  for  it  en-  electrical  conductor,  and  that  the 

abled  him   to   effect   a  connection  velocity  of  the  propagation  of  this 

between  the  electro-magnetic  and  would  coincide  with  that  of  light 

the  electro-static  or  absolute  system  ^see  Kirchhoff  in  '  Annalen  der  Phy- 

of   measurements.     When    he  sue-  sik  und  Chemie,' 1857;  and  Weber, 

ceeded  in  measuring  this  quantity,  '  Electrodyn.  Maasbest.,'  1864).    It 

it  was  found  that  the  figure  for  the  was  reserved  for  Clerk  Maxwell  to 

constant,  which  meant  a  velocity,  point  to  the  real  physical  interpre- 
was  practically  the  same  as  that  for  '  tation  of  Weber's  constant.  Of 

the  velocity  of  the  propagation  of  this  I  shall  speak  in  a  later  chapter 
light.  Weber  himself  does  not  seem  !  (see  Maxwell's  memoir  '  On  Physical 

to  have  attached  any  physical  mean-  Lines  of  Force,'  1862,  reprinted  in 

ing  to  this  coincidence  :  later  he  and  '  Scientific  Papers,'  vol.  i. ) 
Kirchhoff  remarked  that  under  cer- 


THE   ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        373 


regarding  the  equivalence  of  closed  electrical  currents 
with  magnets.  This  led,  first,  to  the  reduction  of  all 
magnetic  effects  to  the  action  of  electrical  currents ;  and, 
secondly,  to  the  enunciation  of  a  fundamental  law  of  the 
interaction  of  two  elements  of  electricity  in  motion.  A 
third  leading  idea  was  that  of  reducing  the  interaction 
of  all  bodies  to  that  of  the  mutual  action  of  pairs  of 
bodies.  This  idea  could  in  general  be  considered  as 
well  established  and  confirmed  by  experience  on  a  large 
scale."  l 

This  leads  me  to  another  and  a  final  remark  on  the 
view  of  natural  phenomena,  first  introduced  by  New- 
ton's gravitation  formula,  which  has  been  so  success- 
ful in  the  calculation  of  all  the  movements  of  cosmic  39. 

,      ,.  ,       ,  .   ,      .         ,  Necessity  of 

bodies,  and  which  in  the  eyes  of  such  a  great  authority  developing 

J    theinflni- 

as  Laplace  contained  the  clue  to  an  explanation  also  of 
molar  and  molecular  phenomena.2     This  view  calculates 


1  '  Electrodynamische     Maasbes- 
timmungen,'  1878,  p.  645. 

2  Although  Weber  followed   the 
lines  so  deeply  impressed  upon  the 
whole  of   Continental  thought  by 
the    labours    of    Laplace    and    his 
school,  it  does   not   seem  that  he 
held  the  same  exalted   opinion  of 
the  value  of  any  mathematical  for- 
mula as  did  Laplace.     Though  he 
looked   upon    his   electro  -  dynamic 
law  as  well  established  by  experi- 
ment    and     valuable     in     guiding 
further  research,  he  was  fully  im- 
pressed with  the  fact  that  all  such 
formulae    are    merely    provisional. 
Thus  he  says  in  the  first  part  of 
his  researches,  written  in  the  year 
1846 :    "  It    seems   to   follow    that 
the  immediate  interaction  of   two 
electrical  particles  does  not  depend 
upon  these  alone,  but  also  upon  the 
presence  of  third  bodies.  ...  It  is 


conceivable  that  the  forces  com- 
prised in  the  discovered  funda- 
mental law  may  be  partly  the 
forces  which  two  electrical  particles 
exert  indirectly  on  each  other,  and 
which  therefore  depend  on  the  in- 
tervening medium.  .  .  .  The  general 
law  for  the  determination  of  the 
acting  forces  might  perhaps  be  yet 
more  simply  expressed  by  taking 
the  intervening  medium  into  ac- 
count, than  has  been  possible 
without  it  in  the  fundamental 
law  now  established.  The  explora- 
tion of  the  intervening  medium, 
which  might  afford  an  insight  into 
many  other  matters,  can  alone  give 
an  answer  to  this  question.  ...  A 
hope  now  exists  that  it  will  be 
possible,  in  several  new  ways,  to 
gain  some  information  as  to  the 
neutral  electric  fluid  which  per- 
vades everything.  Perhaps  in 


374  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

the  actions  of  large  masses  and  complicated  systems  of 
bodies  by  a  process  of  summation  from  the  interaction  of 
units  placed  in  the  simplest  relation — that  of  two  and 
two,  pushing  or  pulling  each  other  in  a  straight   line. 
Now,  in  consequence  of  the  great  distances  at  which  we 
are  placed  from  the  heavenly  bodies,  these  appear  to  us 
as  mere  points,  and  the  observation  of  their  movements, 
their  orbits,  and  their  periods  enabled  astronomers  like 
Kepler,  and  mathematicians  like  Xewton,  to  gain  by  mere 
observation  and  subsequent  calculation  an  idea  of  the 
elementary  rule  which  masses,  considered  to  be  concen- 
trated in  points,  follow  in  their  motion  in  a  connected 
system.     The  next  step  was  to  see  how  these  elementary 
actions  would  add  up  in  cases  where  the  dimensions  of 
the  moving  bodies  were  not  vanishingly  small  in  com- 
parison with  their  distances.      The  infinitesimal  methods, 
invented  in  the  age  of  Newton,  and  developed  by  him 
and  others  into  a  special  calculus,  came  to  the  aid  of 
mathematicians,   and   enabled    them    to    calculate    from 
elementary  data  the  motions  and  phenomena  of  extended 
bodies  and  systems  of  bodies.     These  could  afterwards 
be  actually  measured,  thereby  confirming  the  elementary 
formulae  and  assumptions  which  had  formed  the  basis  of 
those   calculations.     As   already  remarked,  this   process 

other   bodies,   which  are  not   con-  ing  ether  which  contains  and  pro- 

ductors,  there  exist,  not  currents,  pagates  luminous  vibrations,  or  at 

but  only  vibrations,  which  may  in  !   least  that  the  two  are  so  intimately 

future  be  observed  by  the  methods  connected  that  the  observation  of 


indicated  above.     Further,  I  need 


luminous  vibrations  mav  afford  some 


only  point  to  Faraday's  recent  dis-  information  regarding  the  proper- 

covery  of  the  influence  of  electric  '   ties  of  the  noutral  electric  medium." 

currents  on  the  vibrations  of  light,  I    He   then   refers   to  Ampere's  own 

which  makes  it  probable  that  the  i   suggestion  in  this  direction.    ('Elec- 

all-prevadiug  neutral  electric  medi-  trodynamische  Maasbestimmungen,' 

um  itself  constitutes  the  all-prevad-  Part  I.,  p.  169.) 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.        375 


the  basis  of 
cal 
lomy. 


of  confirmation  occupied  a  long  period,  during  which  it 
became  more  and  more  satisfactory  and  complete.  In 
fact,  so  great  has  the  coincidence  of  calculation  with 
observation  turned  out  to  be,  in  all  problems  of  physical 
astronomy,  that  no  astronomer  at  the  end  of  this  century  40. 

The  Newton- 
doubts  that  the  gravitation  formula  alone  will  suffice  to  ian  formula 

explain  all  anomalies  which  still  exist  in  great  number 
in  the  movements  of  cosmic  bodies — such,  for  instance, 
as  the  moon. 

Moreover,  in  the  whole  wide  range  of  physical  and 
chemical,  not  to  speak  of  other  natural  phenomena,  there 
is  probably  no  instance  of  a  simple  mathematical  rela- 
tion having  been  applied  to  so  large  a  field  of  facts, 
found  so  trustworthy  a  guide,  and  been  so  unfailingly 
verified. 

And  yet  the  very  extent  of  this  field  must  not  blind 
us  to  the  fact  that  for  the  explanation  of  molecular1 


1  This  is  indeed  not  to  be  won- 
dered at  when  we  consider  that  in 
all  molecular  and  molar  phenomena 
such  a  variety  of  elements  and  forces 
come  into  play  that  it  is  impossible 
to  isolate  any  special  quantities  as 
we  do  when  from  the  cosmic  point 
of  view  we  lose  sight  of  everything 
except  mass,  time,  and  distance — 
i.e.,  the  elementary  factors  of  our 
system  of  measurement.  In  the 
phenomena  of  electricity,  for  in- 
stance, it  is  merely  by  a  process  of 
mental  abstraction,  which  has  no 
counterpart  in  the  observable  phe- 
nomena, that  we  speak  of  electrical 
masses,  be  they  one  or  two ;  of 
fluids ;  of  elements  of  currents, 
which  in  nature  cannot  exist  alone  ; 
of  velocities  of  a  something  which 
as  yet  cannot  be  clearly  denned. 
Any  mathematical  formula  can 
under  such  conditions  be  merely 


tentative,  and  the  preciseness  of  it 
must  not  hide  from  us  the  fact  that 
it  is  based  upon  hypothetical  rela- 
tions and  artificial  definitions.  This 
was,  for  the  gain  of  scientific 
thought,  very  clearly  brought  out 
in  the  theoretical  discussions  which 
followed  upon  Helmholtz's  critical 
examination  of  Weber's  and  kindred 
formula;,  and  is  well  expressed  by 
Carl  Neumann:  "Electrical  mat- 
ters"— if  such  there  be  —  "never 
exists  alone,  but  only  in  combina- 
tion with  ponderable  matter."  Any 
law  like  that  of  Weber  can  there- 
fore be  merely  a  "  particular,"  not 
a  "fundamental"  or  "universal" 
law,  for  it  refers  merely  to  a  small 
portion  of  the  properties,  forces, 
and  relations  of  electric  and  pon- 
derable matter,  leaving  others — as, 
for  instance,  those  between  electric- 
ity and  heat,  electricity  and  light, 


376 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


phenomena,  or  even  for  such  processes  as  happen  con- 
tinually under  our  eyes  and  our  hands,  this  universal 
law  of  gravitation  has  practically  done  nothing.  The 
action  of  gravitation  alone  between  masses  which  we 
can  manipulate  directly  is  so  weak  that  it  takes  the  very 
finest  instruments  to  detect  it  at  all,  and  at  molecular 
distances  it  is  so  immeasurably  small  that  it  is  hardly 
conceivable  how  it  can  explain  the  existence  of  those 
enormous  forces  with  which  we  here  have  to  deal.1  If 


&c. — more  or  less  in  the  dark  (see 
'  Mathematische  Annalen,'  vol.  xi. 
p.  323).  From  a  philosophical  point 
of  view  these  discussions,  in  which 
many  other  eminent  leaders  of 
scientific  thought  took  part,  are 
of  great  interest  and  importance, 
as  they  bear  upon  the  value  of 
mathematical  formulae  in  physical 
research,  upon  the  definition  of 
laws  of  nature,  the  extent  of  their 
applicability,  the  correct  lines  of  fut- 
ure research,  the  use  of  analogies  in 
the  formation  of  physical  theories, 
&c.  I  therefore  refer  here  to  the 
literature  of  the  subject :  Tait, 
'  Sketch  of  Thermodynamics'  (1868, 
pp.  57,  76);  Thomson  and  Tait, 
'Natural  Philosophy'  (1st  ed.,  p. 
311);  Carl  Neumann,  'Die  Prin- 
cipien  der  Electrodynamik '  (Tub- 
ingen, 1868);  Helmholtz  in  various 
memoirs  from  1872  onwards,  all 
collected  in  '  Wissenschaftliche  Ab- 
handlungen '  (vol.  i.  pp.  545,  636, 
774,  &c.)  and  in  'Vortrage  und 
Reden '  (voL  ii.  Faraday  Lecture) ; 
Carl  Neumann,  '  Mathematische 
Annalen'  (voL  xi.  p.  318).  See 
also  Riecke  on  '  Wilhelm  Weber ' 
(Gottingen,  1892),  and  Clerk  Mas- 
well,  'Electricity  and  Magnetism,' 
(vol.  ii.  last  chapter) ;  '  Elementary 
Treatise  on  Electricity'  (p.  51). 

1  An  interesting  speculation  as  to 
whether  the  Newtonian  formula  of 
gravitation  is  capable  of  explaining 


cohesion  and  capillary  attraction 
will  be  found  in  Thomson's  (Lord 
Kelvin's)  paper  to  the  Royal  Society 
of  Edinburgh  (1862),  and  in  his  lec- 
ture before  the  Royal  Institution 
(1866),  on  Capillary  Attraction,  both 
reprinted  in  the  first  volume  of 
'  Popular  Lectures  and  Addresses.' 
He  there  shows  that  if  we  combine 
Newton's  law  with  the  assumption 
of  an  ultimate  heterogeneousness  of 
matter, — as  is  demanded  in  the  so- 
called  atomic  theory  used  in  chem- 
istry,— the  mass  of  ultimate  por- 
tions of  matter  at  vanishing  dis- 
tances, or  what  is  called  in  contact, 
may  give  rise  to  molecular  forces  of 
attraction  of  any  magnitude ;  since 
the  Newtonian  attraction  depends 
on  two  data — the  distance  and  the 
density  (or  mass)  of  attracting  par- 
ticles. He  concludes  by  saying  that 
"  it  is  satisfactory  to  find  that,  so 
far  as  cohesion  is  concerned,  no 
other  force  than  that  of  gravitation 
need  be  assumed ;'  (p.  63).  It  does 
not  seem  that  this  view,  which  was 
also  held  by  Sir  John  Herschel,  is 
generally  adopted  by  physicists  (see 
Todhunter  and  Pearson,  '  History 
of  the  Theory  of  Elasticity,'  vol.  i. 
p.  418,  &c. ;  vol.  ii.  art.  1650).  An- 
other interesting  speculation  arose 
out  of  the  discussion  over  Weber's 
law.  One  of  the  objections  started 
by  Helmholtz  against  Weber's  law 
was  that,  under  certain  conditions, 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW    OF   NATURE.        377 


for  the  purpose  of  discovering  the  forces  which  exist  in 
the  universe  between  cosmic  bodies  we  had  been  con- 
fined to  experiments  in  the  laboratory,  as  we  are  in  all 
other  departments  of  physics  and  chemistry,  it  is  very  «. 

J    The  Newton- 

doubtful  whether  this  universal  law  of  gravitation  would  ian  formula 

unique  as  to 

ever  have  been  discovered.  And  yet  it  stands  there  as  and 
almost  the  only  formula  universally  applicable  to  all  acy' 
matter  throughout  the  visible  and  tangible  universe. 

In  the  foregoing  pages  I  have  sometimes  spoken  of  this 
great  discovery  of  Newton,  on  which  is  based  the  astron- 
omical view  of  nature,  as  a  formula,  sometimes  as  a  law. 
A  formula  is  merely  the  expression  in  definite  terms  of 
certain  relations  of  measurable  quantities.  By  a  law 
we  are  apt  to  understand  something  more — viz.,  the 
statement  of  some  fundamental,  all-pervading  property 
of  the  things  of  nature,  which,  so  far  as  we  are  con- 
cerned, is  final.1  Whether  the  human  mind  is  at  all 


this  expression  would  give  an  in- 
finite value  for  the  force  between 
electrical  particles  in  motion. 
Weber  replied  that  the  same  argu- 
ment could  be  used  against  the 
gravitation  formula,  and  hinted  at 
the  possibility  that  a  correction 
might  have  to  be  added  to  the  New- 
tonian formula  to  make  it  appli- 
cable to  molecular  distances  ( '  Elec- 
trodyn.  Maasb.,'  1871,  p.  60).  This 
idea  was  taken  up  by  several  Con- 
tinental mathematicians  (see  Isen- 
krahe. '  Das  Riithsel  von  der  Schwer- 
kraft,'  p.  33,  &c.  ;  Paul  du  Bois- 
Reymond,  '  Ueber  die  Grundlagen 
der  Erkenntniss,'  p.  50  ;  Tisserand, 
'Comptes  Rendus,' September  1872). 
1  Helmholtz  says,  referring  to 
Weber's  so  -  called  law :  "If  we 
are  to  consider  Weber's  law  as  an 
elementary  law,  as  an  expression 
of  the  ultimate  cause  of  the  phe- 


nomena to  which  it  refers,  and  not 
merely  as  an  approximately  correct 
expression  of  facts  within  narrow 
limits,  then  we  must  demand  that, 
if  applied  to  objects  of  the  largest 
imaginable  dimensions,  it  should 
give  results  which  are  physically 
possible"  (1873,  ' Wissenschaf tliche 
Abhandlungen,'  vol.  i.  p.  658).  This 
sentence  raises  a  philosophical  ques- 
tion as  to  the  demands  which  we 
can  legitimately  expect  to  be  satis- 
fied by  any  so-called  law  of  nature 
expressible  in  the  symbols  of  hu- 
man thought,  be  these  words  or 
algebraic  signs.  I  venture  to  think 
that  nowadays,  and  largely  in  con- 
sequence of  discussions  similar  to 
those  carried  on  over  Weber's  law, 
physicists  do  not  any  longer  expect 
to  find  laws  of  that  general  and 
fundamental  character  which  the 
words  given  above  describe. 


378  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

capable  of  finding  out  the  ultimate  properties  of  things, 

is    a    question   which   has   been    answered    in    opposite 

«.        ways.     But  whatever  the  answer  may  be  to  this  philo- 

Is  the  New- 

muif^or  sophical  question,  the  further  and  more  modest  ques- 
uitimate  fton  can  ^  ^^g^  j)oes  the  gravitation  formula  express 
one  of  those  universal  facts  which  we  have  to  accept 
as  final,  beyond  or  behind  which  we  cannot  penetrate  ? 
Opposite  answers  have  been  given  to  this  question.  But 
it  stands  very  much  in  the  same  position  in  which 
Laplace  left  it  when  he  said : l  "  The  extreme  difficulty 
of  the  problem  referring  to  the  system  of  the  universe 
obliges  us  to  have  recourse  to  approximations,  which 
leave  room  for  the  fear  that  the  neglected  quantities 
may  have  a  sensible  influence  on  the  results.  As  soon 
as  mathematicians  by  observation  became  aware  of  this 
influence  they  returned  to  their  analysis :  by  rectifying 
the  same  they  have  always  found  the  cause  of  the  ob- 
served anomalies ;  they  have  determined  the  laws  of 
these,  and  frequently  they  have  outrun  observation  by 
discovering  irregularities  which  had  not  yet  been  ob- 
served. The  lunar  theory,  the  theory  of  Saturn,  of 
Jupiter  and  his  satellites,  offer  many  examples  of  this 
43.  kind.2  Thus  we  may  say  that  nature  herself  has  helped 
opinion.3  in  perfecting  the  astronomical  theories  founded  upon  the 


1  Exposition    du     Systeme     du  J   trouve  arretee  par  la  difficult*  que 

Monde,'  6th  ed.,  p.  318.  nous  venons   de  developper;   deja 

'-'  Tisserand,  in  discussing  the  diffi-  a  1'epoque  de  Clairaut  la  gravita- 

culties  which  still  beset  the  lunar  tion  universelle  paraissait  impuis- 

theory,  and  after  referring  to  the  sante  a   expliquer    le    mouvement 

"pfix  Damoiseau  "  offered  by  the  du  peVigee;  elle  triomphera  encore 

Academy  of  Sciences  for  an  essay  !  du  nouvel  obstacle  qui  se  presente 

on    this    subject,    says    ('Bulletin  !   aujourd'hui,  mais  il  reste  a  faire  une 

astronomique,'    1891,    vol.    viiL    p.  ,   belle  decouverte." 

501):   "La  theorie  de   la  lune  se  i 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL   VIEW    OF    NATUKE.        379 

principle  of  universal  gravitation.  This  is,  in  my  opinion, 
one  of  the  greatest  proofs  of  the  truth  of  this  admirable 
principle.  As  to  this  principle,  is  it  a  primordial  law 
of  nature  ?  Is  it  only  a  general  effect  of  an  unknown 
cause  ?  Here  the  ignorance  in  which  we  are  as  to  the 
ultimate  properties  of  matter  stops  us,  and  removes  all 
hope  that  we  shall  ever  be  able  to  answer  these  questions 
in  a  satisfactory  manner." 

In  the  meantime,  as  I  have  tried  to  show,  the  clue 
afforded  by  this  principle  has  led  physicists  by  strict 
analysis,  by  observation,  by  cleverly  arranged  experi- 
ments as  well  as  by  guesses  drawn  from  analogy,  to  the 
discovery  of  many  unknown  phenomena,  to  the  fixing  in 
mathematical  language  of  interesting  relations,  and  in 
general  to  a  large  extension  of  the  field  of  natural  know- 
ledge. No  wonder  that  a  principle  which  has  done,  and 
is  still  doing,  such  valuable  service  in  physical  astronomy 
should  have  done  much  to  establish  the  astronomical 
view  of  nature.1  As  one  of  the  latest  representatives  of 
physical  science  abroad  has  said,  "  The  present  generation 


1  This  view  was  concisely  put  by 
Poisson  at  a  time  when  the  corpus- 
cular theory  of  the  imponderables 
— light,  heat,  and  electricity — still 
reigned  supreme  in  the  Continental 
school :  "  Toutes  les  parties  de  la 
maticre  sont  soumises  a  deux  sortes 
d'actions  mutuelles.  L'une  est  at- 
tractive, independante  de  la  nature 
des  corps,  proportiounelledu  produit 
des  masses,  et  en  raison  inverse  du 
carre"  des  distances :  elle  sVtend 
iudofiniment  dans  1'espace,  et  pro- 
duit la  pesanteur  universelle  et 
tous  les  phenomenes  d'equilibre  et 
du  mouveruent  qui  sont  du  ressort 
de  la  me'canique  celeste.  L'autre 


est  attractive  et  repulsive ;  elle 
de'pend  de  la  nature  des  particules 
et  de  leur  quantite"  de  chaleur ; 
son  intensite  ddcroit  tres  rapide- 
ment  quand  la  distance  augmente, 
et  devient  insensible,  des  que  la 
distance  a  acquis  une ,  grandeur 
sensible"  ('Journal  del'Ecole  poly- 
technique,'  cahier  xx,  p.  4,  1831). 
See  also  Clerk  Maxwell,  '  On  the 
Equilibrium  of  Elastic  Solids'  (1850, 
reprinted  in  '  Scientific  Papers,'  vol. 
i.  p.  30),  where  a  similar  assumption 
is  stated  as  the  basis  of  the  mathe- 
matical theories  of  Navier,  Poisson, 
Lame",  and  Clapeyrou. 


380 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


is  still  more  or  less  accustomed  to  think  in  the  manner  of 
Xewton's  view  of  nature,  in  which  the  supposition  of 
forces  acting  at  a  distance  appears  as  the  most  simple 
view:  we  feel  it  difficult  to  step  out  of  this  circle  of 
ideas."1  [Nevertheless,  the  country  itself  which  produced 


1  Kundt,  '  Die  neuere  Entwick- 
ItiDg  der  Electricitatslehre '  (Berlin, 
1891,  p.  35).  This  habit  is  prob- 
ably more  marked  on  the  Continent 
than  in  England.  In  this  country 
the  later  developments  of  Laplace's 
astronomical  view  of  nature  have 
remained  unknown  except  to  a  few 
scientific  specialists.  Through  Fara- 
day's influence,  and  in  consequence 
of  the  backwardness  which  the 
English  school  of  science  exhibited 
early  in  the  century  in  assimilating 
Continental  ideas  (see  p.  232,  note), 
theoretical  views  on  electricity  as 
well  as  on  other  forms  of  energy 
were  formed  and  taught  more  in 
conformity  with  experimental  ob- 
servation. I  am  not  aware  that 
Weber's  theory  was  expounded  in 
any  English  text-book  or  handbook 
before  Maxwell  referred  to  it  as  the 
view  to  which  Faraday  and  he  him- 
self were  opposed.  In  fact,  the 
astronomical  view  of  molecular 
physics  is  almost  entirely  of  foreign 
growth.  In  England  "  action  at  a 
distance"  is  now  stigmatised  as  a 
pernicious  heresy  (Tait, '  Properties 
of  Matter,'  2nd  ed.,  1890,  Introduc- 
tion) or  as  unthinkable  (O.  Lodge, 
'  Modern  Views  of  Electricity,' 
1892,  p.  386,  Ac.)  Abroad  weighty 
authorities  have  pronounced  against 
the  astronomical  view  of  nature  as 
final  or  even  helpful  in  the  present 
stage  of  physical  and  chemical 
science.  Helmholtz,  who  was 
trained  in  it,  gradually  emanci- 
pated himself,  probably  under  the 
influence  of  physiological  studies  ; 
so  did  KirchhofF,  who  in  his  lectures 
on  Electricity  (edited  by  Planck, 
1891)  hardly  mentions  Weber?  law, 


though  he  had  previously,  in  1857, 
baaed    an    elaborate   and   valuable 
investigation  upon  it  ('Ueber  die 
Bewegung  der  Electricitat  in  Drah- 
ten,' '  Gesammelte  Abhandlungen,' 
p.  131,  &c.)     Still  more  marked  is 
the   aversion    to    the   attitude    or 
habit  of  thought  which  belongs  to 
the  astronomical  view  of  nature  on 
the  part  of  those  who  approached 
physical  problems  from  the  side  of 
chemistry.      Hittorf    (quoted     by 
Lehmann, '  Molecularphysik,'  voL  ii. 
p.  456)  explains  the  opposition  of 
Berzelius  to  Faraday's  electrolytic 
law  and  to  his  other  results  from 
the  fact  that  they  stood  in  direct 
opposition  to  that  view  "  which  at 
the  end  of   the   last  century  had 
been    introduced    into     chemistry 
through  the   success  of   Newton's 
law  in  astronomy,  and  under  the 
influence  of  Laplace  on  Lavoisier 
and  Berthollet,"  and  sees  the  im- 
portance    of     his     own     laborious 
researches    in    the    demonstration 
"that    the     mysterious     potential 
energy  cannot  in  the  case  of  un- 
combined  chemical  substances   be 
explained  by  the  work  of  attractive 
forces,"  and  "that  a  confession  of 
ignorance  in  such  matters  is  more 
conducive  to  progress  than  the  as- 
sertion that  every  process  in  nature 
is  essentially  a  phenomenon  of  at- 
traction in  the  Newtonian  sense." 
Of  Ostwald's  endeavours  to  liberate 
theoretical  views  in  chemistry  from 
the  tyranny  of  the  older  hypotheses 
I   shall   have  frequent  occasion  to 
speak.     His  discourse  '  Die  Energie 
und    ihre    Wandlungen'    (Leipzig, 
1888)    contains    an    expression    of 
opinion  similar  to  those  quoted  here. 


THE    ASTRONOMICAL    VIEW    OF    NATURE.         381 

the  author  of  this  the  astronomical  view  of  nature  has       44. 

Opposition 

also  been  the  birthplace  of  a  different  manner  of  regard-  to  the  astro- 
nomical 

ing  physical  phenomena.  It  will  be  the  object  of  a  future 
chapter  to  trace  the  origin  and  growth  of  what  I  propose 
to  call  the  physical  view  of  nature.  We  shall  then  learn 
how  the  germs  of  this  different  view  can  be  traced  even 
in  the  writings  of  Newton.  But  before  I  take  up  this 
subject  I  must  deal  with  another  and  independent  way 
of  regarding  nature  which  very  largely  supplemented  the 
astronomical  view.  If  the  Newtonian  gravitation  formula 
is  the  basis  and  principle  of  physical  astronomy — of  our 
knowledge  of  cosmic  phenomena — the  view  I  am  now 
going  to  explain  has  been  equally  useful  in  building  up 
another  most  important  science  of  modern  times — the 
science  of  chemistry. 


382 


CHAPTER  V. 


THE   ATOMIC   VIEW   OF   NATUKE. 


i.        IN  the  last  chapter  I  have  shown  how.  under  the  influence 

Recapitula- 
tion. Of  the  Newtonian  philosophy,  the  ancient  but  indefinite 

ideas  of  Attraction  and  Repulsion  acquired  a  definite 
meaning,  and  how — at  least  so  far  as  cosmical  phenom- 
ena are  concerned — the  Newtonian  Gravitation  formula 
was  made  the  foundation  of  very  successful  explanations l 


1  I  use  the  word  explanation  in 
conformity  with  the  popularly  ac- 
cepted meaning  of  the  term.  It  is, 
however,  well  to  remark  here  that,  in 
the  course  of  our  century  and  greatly 
owing  to  the  influence  of  the  exact 
scientific  spirit,  a  change  is  being 
gradually  introduced  into  language, 
which  will  assist  in  conveying  more 
correct  views  as  to  the  objects  of 
science.  In  England  the  meta- 
physical interest  has  been  so  long 
banished  from  scientific  literature, 
the  part  also  which  experiment  and 
observation  have  played  has  been 
so  great,  that  misunderstandings  as 
to  the  real  objects  of  science  have 
been  less  frequent  than  abroad, 
especially  in  Germany,  where  the 
metaphysical  or  philosophical  in- 
terest still  largely  pervades  scien- 
tific literature,  though  metaphysics 
themselves  may  be  on  the  decline. 
There  the  definition  of  the  science 


of  mechanics  (now  more  usually 
termed  dynamics  in  this  country), 
given  by  Kirchhoffin  his  '  Vorlesun- 
gen  iiber  mathematische  Physik ' 
(vol.  i.  p.  1),  has  marked  quite  an 
epoch  in  the  philosophy  of  the  ex- 
act sciences.  This  definition  is  as 
follows  :  "  Mechanics  is  the  science 
of  motion  ;  we  can  assign  as  its 
object :  to  describe  completely  and 
in  the  simplest  manner  the  motions 
which  occur  in  nature."  Inas- 
much as  a  large  school  of  natural 
philosophers  consider  that  it  is  the 
object  of  all  exact  sciences  to  give 
a  mechanical  explanation  of  natural 
phenomena,  it  would  follow  that 
the  object  of  all  science  is  to  re- 
duce the  phenomena  of  nature  to 
forms  of  motion,  and  to  describe 
these  completely  and  in  the  simplest 
manner.  We  may  feel  some  re- 
luctance in  assenting  at  once  to 
this  definition.  Still  an  analysis  of 


THE   ATOMIC    VIEW    OF   NATURE. 


383 


of  nature.  Towards  the  end  of  the  last  century,  and  all 
through  the  present  one,  this  view  of  things  natural,  which 
I  have  called  the  Astronomical  view,  has  exerted  a  great 
fascination  over  scientific  minds :  especially  in  the  mathe- 
matical schools  of  Trance  and  the  Continent  it  has  been 
a  leading  idea  in  scientific  thought.  It  has  been  ex- 
tended into  molar  and  molecular  physics,  and  has  in 
these  led  to  some  very  extraordinary  and  ingenious 
theories.  In  England,  this  astronomical  view  of  Nature 
has,  in  the  course  of  the  present  century,  been  received 


what  has  been  done  since  Newton 
in  real  science  will  probably  con- 
vince us  that  the  definition  is  safe 
and  sufficient.  It  means  the  an- 
alysis of  phenomena  as  to  their 
appearance  in  space  and  their  se- 
quence in  time.  Both  can,  in  con- 
sequence of  the  small  number  of 
elementary  relations  on  which 
arithmetic,  geometry,  and  dynam- 
ics are  built  up,  be  reduced  to 
— or  described  in — a  small  num- 
ber of  elementary  terms  or  concep- 
tions, the  alphabet  of  all  science. 
To  show  how  in  every  instance  the 
terms  of  this  alphabet  are  to  be  put 
together,  in  order  to  correspond  to 
any  phenomenon,  is  all  the  explana- 
tion we  can  give.  Objections  have 
been  raised  to  Kirchhoff's  definition 
by  Du  Bois-Reymond  ("  Gothe  und 
kein  Ende,"  in  'Reden,'  vol.  i. 
p.  434),  inasmuch  as  it  does  not 
define  the  difference  between  the 
descriptive  (historical)  and  the  ex- 
act (mathematical)  sciences  of  na- 
ture ;  but  the  difference  is  really 
maintained  if  we  demand  a  com- 
plete description.  Natural  history 
only  affords  an  incomplete  descrip- 
tion. The  only  complete  descrip- 
tion is  that  afforded  by  a  mathe- 
matical formula  in  which  the  con- 
stants are  supplied  by  observation. 
This  permits  us  to  calculate  those 


features  or  phases  of  phenomena 
which  are  hidden  from  our  obser- 
vation in  space  or  in  time.  An 
objection  to  the  view  which  identi- 
fies physics  with  mechanics,  seems 
implied  in  Mach's  remarks  con- 
tained in  the  last  chapter  of  his 
very  thoughtful  book  'Die  Me- 
chanik  in  ihrer  Entwickelung ' 
(Leipzig,  1889).  According  to  his 
view,  the  aim  of  exact  science  is 
not  necessarily  to  give  mechanical 
explanations  or  descriptions  of  phe- 
nomena, inasmuch  as  temperature, 
electric  potential,  &c. ,  are  just  as 
simple  elements  of  natural  phenom- 
ena as  mass  and  motion.  It  seems, 
nevertheless,  that  exact  measure- 
ments are  only  possible  in  the 
data  of  time  and  space.  Assum- 
ing that  a  complete  and  simple 
description — admitting  of  calcula- 
tion— is  the  aim  of  all  exact  science, 
it  is  evident  how  much  and  how 
little  we  may  expect  from  science. 
We  shall  not  expect  to  find  the 
ultimate  and  final  causes,  and 
science  will  not  teach  us  to  under- 
stand nature  and  life.  The  search 
after  ultimate  causes  may  perhaps 
be  given  up  as  hopeless ;  that 
after  the  meaning  and  significance 
of  the  things  of  life  will  never  be 
abandoned :  it  is  the  philosophical 
or  religious  problem. 


384  SCIENTIFIC    THOCTGHT. 

with  less  favour,  although  it  was  entirely  owing  to 
Newton's  gravitation  formula  that  it  ever  obtained  its 
great  influence,  the  labour  of  Continental  men  of  science 
being  very  largely  spent  in  two  directions  :  first,  in  draw- 
ing the  purely  mathematical  consequences  of  Newton's 
formula — in  this  they  have  met  with  increasing  success, 
unparalleled  by  that  in  any  other  domain  of  science ; 
and  secondly,  in  extending  the  principle  of  Xewton,  by 
experiment  and  analogy,  into  other  departments.  In  some 
of  these,  very  remarkable  results  have  been  achieved  ;  but 
nevertheless  at  the  end  of  the  century  no  extension  or 
analogue  of  the  Newtonian  gravitation  formula  has  been 
generally  accepted,  and  it  still  stands  there  as  almost 
the  only  firmly  established  mathematical  relation,  ex- 
pressive of  a  property  of  all  matter,  to  which  the  pro- 
gress of  more  than  two  centuries  has  added  nothing, 
from  which  it  has  taken  nothing  away.  The  value, 
however,  of  all  those  partial  attempts  in  another  direc- 
tion has  been  enormous ;  for  with  the  aim  of  applying, 
extending,  or  modifying  a  rigorous  mathematical  for- 
mula, those  philosophers  have  carried  out  a  series  of 
the  most  exact  observations  and  measurements  of  physi- 
cal quantities,  very  greatly  extended  our  knowledge  of 
natural  phenomena  and  their  mutual  relations,  and 
founded  that  general  system  of  physical  measurement 
which  is  now  universally  adopted.  The  names  of  Gauss 
and  Weber  stand  out  prominently  as  leaders  in  this 
work.  I  shall  have  to  come  back  to  this  point  later 
on,  after  I  have  shown  that  other  views  of  nature 
besides  the  astronomical  have  also  led  up  to  it,  and 
placed  it  in  similar  prominence. 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


385 


2. 
Atomic 


About  a  century  after  the  publication  of  the  '  Principia,' 
which,  by  propounding  the  gravitation  formula,  raised  the 
ancient  and  indefinite  notion  of  Attraction  to  the  rank  of 
a  useful  and  rigorously  defined  expression,  another  favour- 
ite theory  of  the  ancient  philosophers l  was  similarly  ele- 
vated to  the  rank  of  a  leading  and  useful  scientific  idea. 

Although  no  mathematical  relation  equal  in  value  and 
definiteness  to  the  gravitation  formula  marks  the  intro-  theory, 
duction  of  the  Atomic  theory  in  Chemistry,  it  never- 
theless owes  its  success  to  similar  qualities — viz.,  to  the 
fact  that  it  led  natural  philosophers  to  make  definite 
measurements,  and  put  exact  research  in  the  place  of 
vague  reasoning. 

The  atomic  theory,  usually  associated  with  the  name 
of  Dalton,  is,  however,  not  nearly  as  much  the  historic 
property  of  that  great  man  as  gravitation  is  that  of 
Newton,  for  whereas  the  latter  gave  the  fullest  gen- 
eralisation that  can  so  far  be  safely  made,  the  atomic 


1  Ancient  philosophers  have  fur- 
nished us  with  three  distinct  ab- 
stractions which  have  survived,  and 
which,  put  into  definite  mathemati- 
cal language,  have  led  exact  research 
in  physics  and  chemistry  in  modern 
times  —  the  theory  of  Attraction 
and  Repulsion,  the  Atomic  Theory, 
and  the  Kinetic  Theory,  or  the 
notion  that  everything  is  motion. 
Of  these  three  theories  the  second 
was  most  developed  in  antiquity  ; 
Lucretius's  great  poem  on  the  na- 
ture of  things  being  really  a  treatise 
on  the  subject,  in  which  the  atomic 
view  is  placed  in  the  centre,  the  two 
other  ideas  being  likewise  largely 
utilised.  The  historians  of  ancient 
philosophy  trace  these  abstract  or 
leading  ideas  back  to  the  earlier 
Greek  thinkers.  Thus  Heraclitus 

VOL.  I. 


of  Ephesus  is  credited  with  having 
first  taught  that  everything  is  in 
motion .  E  m  pedocles  of  Agrigentum 
made  use  of  the  notions  of  Attrac- 
tion and  Repulsion,  poetically  re- 
presented as  Love  and  Hatred,  to 
explain  the  action  of  his  elements  ; 
and  Democritus  of  Abdera  is  uni- 
versally considered  to  be  the  true 
founder  of  the  atomistic  theory, 
which  was  adopted  and  developed 
in  the  School  of  Epicurus,  and  very 
fully  explained  by  the  Roman  poet. 
A  very  good  analysis  will  be  found 
in  Lange's '  History  of  Materialism ' 
(English  translation  by  Thomas,  3 
vols. ),  in  which  also  the  historical 
connection  with  modern  thought, 
especially  through  Bacon,  Gassendi, 
and  Hobbes,  is  clearly  brought 
out. 

2B 


386 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


3. 

Lav::s:er. 


theory  has  been  gradually  defined  and  variously  modi- 
fied in  the  course  of  this  century,  and  is  still  in  a  some- 
what unstable  condition.  "We  are  also  bound  to  attach 
the  greatest  importance  to  the  preliminary  step  taken 
by  Lavoisier,  who  is  even  more  justly  called  the  father 
of  modern  chemistry  than  Kepler  is  called  the  father 
of  modern  astronomy. 

The  exact  claims  of  Lavoisier  to  this  important  place  in 
the  history  of  chemistry  have   been  variously  stated : x 


1  Continental  writers  are  pretty 
unanimous  in  dating  modern  chem- 
istry from  the  time  of  Lavoisier 
(1743-1794).  In  this  country  there 
has  been  less  unanimity,  the  names 
of  Black,  of  Cavendish,  of  Priestley, 
even  of  Robert  Boyle,  having  occa- 
sionally been  put  forward.  The 
fact  that  Lavoisier  did  not  suffi- 
ciently acknowledge  r  his  indebted- 
ness to  some  of  his  English  con- 
temporaries has  given  occasion  in 
some  quarters  to  depreciation  of  his 
merits.  It  cannot  be  upheld  that 
he  was  the  first  formally  to  express 
the  doctrine  of  the  indestructibility 
or  conservation  of  matter,  as  this 
idea  underlay  many  experimental 
researches  before  his  time;  nor 
that  he  was  the  first  to  refer  to 
the  balance  as  the  ultimate  test 
of  chemical  facts.  The  assertion 
that  he  first  introduced  the  idea 
of  two  different  kinds  of  matter, 
ponderable  and  imponderable,  is 
also  questionable,  and  still  more 
so  his  claim  to  having  discovered 
oxygen,  the  composition  of  water 
and  of  atmospheric  air,  the  combus- 
tibility of  the  diamond,  and  other 
special  facts.  His  fame  rests  upon 
a  much  broader  basis,  and  has 
been  most  clearly  investigated  and 
settled  by  Hermann  Kopp  in  his 
'  Entwickelung  der  Chemie  in  der 
neueren  Zeit'  (Mtinchen,  1873). 


In  this  excellent  work  the  author 
somewhat    modifies    the    view    he 
took  in  his  earlier  '  Geschichte  der 
Chemie '  (Braunschweig,  1843,  espe- 
cially voL  L  p.  274,  &c.),  and  sums 
up  Lavoisier's  merit  in  the  follow- 
:   ing  words  (p.  145):  "His  contem- 
j   poraries  could  dispose  of  the  same 
!   inherited  and  much  new  material, 

•  but  not  one  of  them  understood 
how  to  build  up  out  of  this  material 
and  his  own  independent  researches 

j   a  chemical  system,  the  reception  of 

•  which   should  form    the    starting- 
'   point  for  all  future  improvement 
j   of  this  science.     Lavoisier  has  the 

whole  merit  of  having  achieved 
this.  He  added  to  his  own  recog- 
'  nition  of  the  correct  views  the  work 
of  procuring  recognition  for  them 
from  others.  He  imparted  his  own 
matured  views  to  those  who  repre- 
sented chemistry  at  the  end  of  the 
last  century.  .  .  .  We  must  measure 
his  greatness  not  merely  by  hia 
own  insight  but  also  by  the  re- 
sistance which  he  had  to  overcome 
in  other  chemists  who  cluru 
the  older  theory.  These  achieve- 
ments are  great  enough  not  to  re- 
quire the  exaggeration  with  which 
they  have  occasionally  been  an- 
nounced, and  not  to  be  touched  by- 
attempts  on  the  other  side  to  mini- 
mise them." 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


387 


there  is  however  no  difference  of  opinion  on  this  point, 
that  since  his  time,  and  greatly  through  his  labours,  the 
quantitative  method  has  been  established  as  the  ultimate 
test  of  chemical  facts ;  the  principle  of  this  method  being 
the  rule  that  in  all  changes  of  combination  and  reaction, 
the  total  weight  of  the  various  ingredients — be  they  ele- 
mentary bodies  or  compounds — remains  unchanged.  The- 
science  of  chemistry  was  thus  established  upon  an  exact, 
a  mathematical  basis.  By  means  of  this  method  Lavoisier, 
utilising  and  analysing  the  results  gained  by  himself  and 
others  before  him,  notably  those  of  Priestley,  Cavendish, 
and  Black,  succeeded  in  destroying  the  older  theory  of 
combustion,  the  so-called  phlogistic  theory.1  From  a 


1  This  result  was  announced  in 
1777  to  the  Paris  Academy,  and 
the  demonstration  completed  in  a 
memoir  of  1783.  "He  closes  this 
latter  memoir  with  the  expression, 
that  his  object  had  been  to  bring 
forward  new  proofs  of  his  theory 
of  combustion  of  1777,  and  to 
prove  that  Stahl's  phlogiston  was 
something  purely  imaginary, — that 
without  it  facts  could  be  more 
easily  and  more  simply  explained 
than  with  it ;  he  did  not  expect 
that  his  views  would  be  at  once 
accepted,  .  .  .  time  would  have 
to  confirm  or  to  reject  the  opinions 
he  had  developed,  but  already  he 
recognised  with  satisfaction  that  un- 
prejudiced students  of  the  science, 
unbiassed  mathematicians  and  phy- 
sicists, believed  no  longer  in  phlo- 
giston as  Stahl  viewed  it,  and  that 
they  considered  the  whole  doctrine 
more  as  a  hindrance  than  as  a  help- 
ful scaffolding  in  erecting  the  edifice 
of  science"  (Kopp,  '  Entwickelung,' 
p.  202).  This  and  the  further  re- 
mark of  Kopp  that  it  was  the 
mathematicians  who  took  up  La- 
voisier's views  (see  supra,  p.  115, 


note  2)  are  significant  signs  of  the 
introduction  of  the  mathematical, 
the  measuring,  spirit  into  chemistry. 
Few  ideas  which  once  exerted  so 
great  and  lasting  an  influence  on 
science  as  that  of  phlogiston,  have 
so  entirely  disappeared  from  our 
text-books,  and  it  is  interesting  to 
note  that  those  whose  researches 
were  guided  by  it  were  not  so  far 
from  grasping  a  valuable  truth 
as  has  been  supposed.  This  theory, 
elaborated  by  Stahl,  a  contem- 
porary of  Newton  and  Leibniz 
(1660-1734),  was  the  first  attempt 
to  co-ordinate  a  great  mass  of  ob- 
servations, to  bring  the  phenomena 
of  chemical  change  under  one  com- 
mon principle.  Phlogiston  was 
the  thing  the  migration  of  which 
gave  rise  to  chemical  change,  and 
as  the  most  obvious  changes  were 
exhibited  in  the  processes  of  com- 
bustion, "  Phlogiston  "or  "  Brenn- 
stoff"  was  the  name  which  sug- 
gested itself  as  most  suitable  for 
this  principle.  Chemical  changes 
were  not  to  be  measured  so  much 
by  the  resulting  change  of  weight 
as  by  the  readiness  with  which 


388 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


4. 

Phlogistic 
theory. 


scientific  point  of  view,  the  principal  defect  in  this  theory 
was,  that  its  explanations  could  not  be  subjected  to  any 
strict  and  exact  numerical  verification.  Whenever  an 
element  enters  into  our  operations  which  has  either  no 
weight  or  a  negative  weight,  and  thus  evades  exact  de- 
termination and  control,  explanations  and  observations 
become  vague  and  uncertain. 

In  the  time  of  Lavoisier,  and  pre-eminently  through  his 
exertions,  this  vague  and  unmeasurable  principle  phlo- 
giston was  eliminated  from  the  laboratory  and  the  text- 
books :  quantities  took  the  place  of  indefinable  qualities, 
and  numerical  determinations  increased  in  frequency  and 
accuracy.  The  vague  phlogistic  theory,  which  contained 
a  germ  of  truth,  but  one  which  at  that  time  could  not  be 
put  into  definite  terms,  had  helped  to  gather  up  many 
valuable  facts  and  observations :  these  were  collected  and 
restated  in  a  new  and  precise  language.  It  has  been  said 
that  every  science  must  pass  through  three  periods  of 
development.  The  first  is  that  of  presentiment,  or  of 
faith ;  the  second  is  that  of  sophistry ;  and  the  third  is 
that  of  sober  research.  Liebig  states  the  case  somewhat 


substances  enter  into  chemical  re- 
action ;  and  the  mobility  or  inert- 
ness of  chemical  substances  was  to 
be  measured  by  the  presence  or  ab- 
sence of  a  definite  something.  A 
hundred  and  fifty  years  after  Stahl, 
science  had  so  far  advanced,  that 
besides  the  change  of  weight  or 
mass,  the  change  of  the  power 
of  entering  into  chemical  com- 
bination could  also  be  measured, 
and  the  term  "  potential  energy  " 
was  introduced  to  describe  many  of 
those  properties  and  processes  which 
Stahl  had  fastened  upon,  when  he, 
as  the  pioneer,  undertook  to  co- 


ordinate chemical  phenomena.  If 
Stahl  considered  phlogiston  to  be 
a  substance,  though  he  did  not  in- 
quire into  its  mass  or  ponderable 
property,  the  question  might  be 
put  again,  whether  "  energy  "  is  not 
to  be  considered  after  all  as  a  sub- 
stance. Cf.  Tait,  '  Properties  of 
Matter'  (2nd  ed.,  introduction,  es- 
pecially p.  5  sqq.) ;  'Recent  Ad- 
vances of  Science,'  introduction; 
also  Clerk  Maxwell,  '  Electricity  and 
Magnetism '  (last  chapter)  ;  Ost- 
wald,  '  Chemische  Energie'  (Leip- 
zig, 1893,  p.  41). 


THE    ATOMIC   VIEW   OP   NATURE.  389 

more  correctly  when  he  says :  "  To  investigate  the  essence 
of  a  natural  phenomenon,  three  conditions  are  necessary: 
We  must  first  study  and  know  the  phenomenon  itself, 
from  all  sides ;  we  must  then  determine  in  what  relation 
it  stands  to  other  natural  phenomena ;  and  lastly,  when 
we  have  ascertained  all  these  relations,  we  have  to  solve 
the  problem  of  measuring  these  relations  and  the  laws  of 
mutual  dependence — that  is,  of  expressing  them  in  num- 
bers. In  the  first  period  of  chemistry,  all  the  powers 
of  men's  minds  were  devoted  to  acquiring  a  knowledge  of 
the  properties  of  bodies ;  it  was  necessary  to  discover, 
observe,  and  ascertain  their  peculiarities.  This  is  the 
alchemistical  period.  The  second  period  embraces  the 
determination  of  the  mutual  relations  or  connections  of 
these  properties ;  this  is  the  period  of  phlogistic  chemistry. 
In  the  third  period,  in  which  we  now  are,  we  ascertain  by 
weight  and  measure  and  express  in  numbers  the  degree 
in  Which  the  properties  of  bodies  are  mutually  dependent. 
The  inductive  sciences  begin  with  the  substance  itself, 
then  come  just  ideas,  and  lastly,  mathematics  are  called 
in,  and,  with  the  aid  of  numbers,  complete  the  work."  l 

As  Galileo,  Huygens,  and  Newton,  by  a  series  of  bril- 
liant investigations  and  theories,  such  as  those  of  the  pen- 
dulum, the  fall  of  bodies,  finally  of  universal  gravitation, 
established  the  usefulness  of  the  mathematical  treatment 
of  physical  phenomena,  so  Lavoisier  and  his  school  proved 
the  correctness  and  usefulness  of  their  views  by  the  new  5. 

Theory  of 

theory  of  combustion,  as  consisting  in  the  combination  of  combustion 
a  special  body  or  element  called  oxygen  with  other  bodies 

1  '  Familiar  Letters  on  Chemistry,'  translated  by  Blyth,  4th  ed.,  London, 
1859,  p.  60. 


390  SCIENTIFIC  THOUGHT. 

or  elements.  A  very  large  field  of  research — all  on  the 
lines  pointed  out  by  the  new  school — was  opened  out.  But 
the  age  for  a  further  application  of  mathematical  reason- 
ing came  much  more  slowjy  in  chemistry  than  in  physical 
science. 

The  latter  had  at  least  one  great  department,  in  which 
a  small  number  of  factors,  all  admitting  of  mathematical 
accuracy — those  of  distance,  mass,  and  motion — sufficed 
to  explain  the  phenomena,  at  least  if  viewed  from  a  great 
distance.  This  science  is  the  physics  of  the  heavens,  the 
science  of  cosmic  phenomena.  On  this  earth — in  physical 
and  still  more  in  chemical  phenomena — the  matter  stood 
very  differently.  Here  we  have  not  to  deal  with  a  few 
measurable  quantities  only.  A  large  number  of  elements 
or  factors,  of  which  only  very  few  can  be  accurately 
measured,  combine  to  make  up  what  we  called  in  the  last 
chapter  molar  and  molecular  phenomena.  In  the  study 
of  inanimate  nature,  astronomy — the  mechanics  of  the 
heavens — deals  with  the  simplest  relations  :  chemistry — 
the  science  of  the  changes  which  bodies  undergo  when 
being  combined  or  separated — deals  with  the  most  com- 
plicated side  of  reality.  Physics  occupy  an  intermediate 
position,  and  thus  we  can  also  trace  in  the  history  of 
physical  research  the  twofold  influence  of  the  astronomical 
method  of  inquiry  on  one  side,  and  the  chemical  on  the 
other. 

But  the  general  rule,  that  in  chemical  changes  the 
weight  of  all  the  constituents  put  together  never  changes, 
was  not  the  only  numerical  relation  which  came  to  the 
aid  of  students  of  nature,  when  they,  at  the  end  of  the  last 
century,  betook  themselves  to  exact  measurements  and 


THE    ATOMIC   VIEW    OF   NATURE. 


391 


determinations.  That  rule  is  indeed  the  foundation  of  all 
work  in  the  laboratory,  the  principle  which  decides  the 
degree  of  accuracy  attained  in  every  analysis,  and  which 
not  infrequently  is  the  only  method  of  determining  the 
presence  of  some  undiscovered  constituent.1  Not  long 


1  The  revolution  in  chemistry  at 
the  end  of  the  last  century  manifests 
itself  in  nothing  more  than  in  the 
various  distinct  problems,  corre- 
sponding to  different  courses  of 
scientific  thought  and  different  in- 
terests, which  have  guided  chemical 
research  since  that  time.  The  first 
definite  object  was  the  search  after 
the  real  elements,  the  attempt  to 
decompose  the  existing  substances 
of  nature  into  their  ultimate  con- 
stituents. This  interesting  occu- 
pation somewhat  pushed  into  the 
background  the  theoretical  investi- 
gations regarding  the  forms  of  the 
combinations  of  the  various  ele- 
ments into  compounds,  still  more 
the  study  of  chemical  affinity.  A 
second  definite  object  was  the  de- 
velopment of  the  theory  of  combus- 
tion which  Lavoisier  propounded, 
and  the  confirmation  or  refutation 
of  the  idea  according  to  which 
oxygen  occupied  almost  as  import- 
ant a  position  in  chemical  reactions 
as  phlogiston  had  done  before.  A 
third  definiteobject  was  the  develop- 
ment of  analytical  chemistry,  the 
systematic  and  methodical  use  of 
the  balance.  So  far  as  the  first 
branch  of  this  pursuit  was  con- 
cerned, Lavoisier's  catalogue  of  the 
elements  was  still  very  incomplete  ; 
it  contained  thirty-three  members, 
including  light  and  heat,  and 
twenty-three  of  the  substances 
which  now  figure  in  the  list  of  the 
seventy  elements  enumerated  in  the 
text-books  ;  the  alkalies  and  earths 
were  still  considered  to  be  simple 
bodies.  A  great  addition  to  our 
knowledge  in  this  department  came 


through  Davy's  decomposition  of 
soda  and  potash.  And  after  his 
proof  of  the  elementary  nature  of 
chlorine  the  oxygen  theory  of  La- 
voisier had  also  to  be  greatly  modi- 
fied. "Through  a  series  of  most 
important  investigations,  he  rose  in 
the  beginning  of  this  century  to 
such  eminence,  that  he  was  then 
considered  to  be  the  first  represen- 
tative of  chemical  science.  With 
great  experimental  ability  he  com- 
bined a  singular  freedom  from  all 
the  theoretical  doctrines  which  were 
recognised  in  his  age"  (Kopp, '  Ent- 
wickelung  der  Chemie,'  p.  451).  In 
this  he  resembled  Dalton  and  Fara- 
day and  other  natural  philosophers 
in  this  country,  on  whom  theoretical 
notions  formed  in  the  Continental 
schools  had  little  or  no  influence. 
Qualitative  analysis  was  less  indebt- 
ed to  Lavoisier  than  other  branches 
of  the  science  were.  In  fact,  it  was 
more  at  home  in  Sweden  and  Ger- 
many, where  the  interests  of  miner- 
alogy and  metallurgy  promoted  it. 
Bergmann  and  Scheele  in  Sweden, 
Klaproth  in  Berlin,  were  the  fore- 
runners of  Berzelius  and  of  the 
Berlin  school  of  analysts.  In  this 
country  Black  and  especially  Caven- 
dish had  carried  out  some  important 
quantitative  determinations,  the  ac- 
curacy of  which  seems  very  far  be- 
hind modern  standards  (see  Kopp, 
'  Geschichte  der  Chemie,'  vol.  ii.  p. 
70,  &c.,  1844).  It  was  the  introduc- 
tion of  the  notion  of  chemical  equi- 
valence, a  term  used  already  by 
Cavendish,  which  furnished  the 
ultimate  test  for  accuracy  and  re- 
volutionised quantitative  analysis. 


392  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT, 

e.        before  the  age  of  Lavoisier,  another  general  conception 

Bole  of  fixed 

proportions,  had  been  introduced  into  chemical  research ;  this  was  the 
rule  of  definite  proportions — i.e.,  the  fact  that  substances, 
whether  simple  or  compound,  combine  only  in  definite 
proportions  of  their  weight,  and  that  the  numbers  marking 
these  proportions  are  characteristic  of  every  definite 
chemical  substance.  It  took  some  time,  nearly  a  century, 
before  this  idea,  which  arose  through  the  examination  of 
neutral  salts  and  the  determination  of  the  quantities  of 
acids  and  alkalies  which  were  wanted  to  effect  mutual 
saturation,  became  clear ;  before  the  rule  of  definite  pro- 
portions was  generally  established,  becoming  a  guide  for 
chemical  analysis.  It  is  interesting  to  note  how  the 
vaguer  terms  of  chemical  affinity  and  elective  attraction, 
of  chemical  action,  of  adhesion  and  elasticity — mostly 
borrowed  from  other  departments  of  science  where  they 
had  definite  meanings — gradually  disappeared,  when  by 
the  aid  of  the  chemical  balance  each  simple  substance 
and  each  definite  compound  began  to  be  characterised, 
and  labelled  with  a  fixed  number.  Nevertheless,  even  at 
the  beginning  of  this  century,  eminent  chemists  were  still 
so  much  engaged  in  discussing  the  rival  claims  of  the  old 
phlogistic,  and  the  modern  theory  of  combustion,  of  Ber- 
thollet's  chemical  equilibrium,  of  the  so-called  dynamical 
and  the  electro-chemical  views  of  phenomena,  that  the  first 
methodical  attempt  actually  to  fix  these  numbers — i.e.,  to 
give  a  table  of  chemical  equivalents — remained  unnoticed.1 

1  The  history  of  chemistry  early  doctrine  of  chemical  affinities,  was 

in  this  century  furnishes  a  good  ex-  evidently  much  influenced  by  the 

ample  of  the  sway  which  theoretical  mathematical  theory  of  attraction, 

views  exercised  over  the  minds  of  in-  and  by  the  mechanical  laws  of  equi- 

vestigators.     Berthollet,  who  began  librium,  which  formed  so  prominent 

by  critically  examining  Bergmanirs  a  subject   of  investigation  in   the 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


393 


The  merit  of  having  made  this  attempt  belongs  to  one 
who  approached  chemistry  entirely  from  the  mathematical 
side,  who  wrote  the  first  chemical  book  with  a  title  point- 
ing directly  to  measurements,  but  who  perhaps  spoilt  his 
work  by  giving  way  to  the  fascination  which  regular 
numerical  and  geometrical  arrangements  have  again  and 
again  exercised  over  philosophical  inquirers.  Jeremias 
Benjamin  Bichter  —  a  name  possessed  of  no  popular  cele- 
brity  —  published  in  1792  to  1794,  in  three  parts,  his 
"  Stcechiometry,  or  the  art  of  measuring  chemical  ele- 
ments." l  From  his  data,  Fischer  calculated  in  1802  the 


7. 


writings  of  Laplace  and  his  school. 
Chemical  affinity  was  to  be  co- 
ordinated with  what  he  called  astro- 
nomical attraction  ;  both  were  to 
be  ultimately  the  same  physical 
property ;  they  acted  differently, 
because  in  the  case  of  gravitation 
the  dimensions  were  so  large,  that 
the  form,  distances,  and  peculiar 
properties  of  the  molecules  had  no 
influence.  It  was  an  attempt  to 
introduce  the  astronomical  view  of 
matter  into  molecular  physics,  and 
to  base  chemistry  upon  this  view. 
Berthollet  adhered  to  the  corpus- 
cular theory  of  heat  against  Rum- 
ford,  who  had  just  propounded  his 
opinion  that  heat  is  not  a  consti- 
tuent part  of  bodies  ;  and  he  main- 
tained that  chemical  affinity  was  a 
function  of  the  mass  of  bodies  as 
was  astronomical  attraction.  The 
germ  of  truth  in  Berthollet's  views, 
which  were  approved  by  Laplace, 
but  cast  into  oblivion  under  the 
influence  of  Proust  and  Richter's 
theory  of  fixed  proportions,  has 
in  recent  times  been  shown  by 
Lothar  Meyer  ('  Modern  Theories  of 
Chemistry,'  Introduction),  and  by 
Ostwald  ('Allgemeine  Chemie,'  vol. 
ii.  p.  557,  1st  ed.,  also  'Die  Energie 
und  ihre  Wandluugen,'  Leipzig, 


1888,  p.  20).  If  the  astronomical 
view  of  molecular  phenomena  pre- 
vented Berthollet  from  accepting 
Proust's  doctrine  of  fixed  proportions 
and  definite  combinations,  Richter 
injured  his  own  reputation  by  ad- 
hering to  the  nomenclature  of  the 
phlogiston  theory  after  it  had  been 
discarded  by  French  chemists,  and 
in  Germany  after  Klaproth's  deter- 
minations in  1792.  The  oxygen 
theory  of  combustion  of  Lavoisier 
got  such  a  firm  hold  on  the  minds 
of  Continental  chemists  that  the 
labours  of  those  who,  like  Cavendish 
in  England  and  Richter  in  Germany, 
put  forward  important  discoveries 
in  the  language  and  on  the  principles 
of  the  older  theory,  were  temporarily 
forgotten.  See  Kopp,  '  Entwickel- 
ung  der  Chemie,'  p.  271,  &c. 

1  Stojchiometry  comes  from  the 
Greek  ra  <rroi\fia.,  the  constituent 
parts,  and  fj.erpf'iv,  to  measure. 
All  Richter's  works  are  connected 
with  the  application  of  mathematics 
to  chemistry  ;  his  inaugural  disser- 
tation, which  appeared  in  1789, 
bearing  the  title  '  de  usu  matheseos 
in  chymia'  (Kopp,  'Geschichte  der 
Chemie,'  vol.  ii.  p.  350).  "  Richter 
etait  preoccupe  de  1'idee  d'appliquer 
les  mathe'matiques  a  la  chimie,  et  en 


394 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


8. 
Dalton. 


first  table  of  chemical  equivalents,  taking  sulphuric  acid 
as  the  standard  with  the  figure  1000. 

The  conviction  that  chemical  substances  combine  ac- 
cording to  fixed  and  simple  proportions  gained  ground 
on  the  Continent,  chiefly  during  the  discussion  in  which 
Proust  finally  disproved  and  defeated  Berthollet's  theory 
of  chemical  affinity ;  but  it  is  to  Dalton  that  the  doctrine 
of  fixed  and  multiple  proportions  is  indebted  for  a  con- 
sistent exposition.  Dalton  based  it  upon  a  mental  re- 
presentation which  ever  since  has  been  the  soul  of  all 
chemical  reasoning. 

When  Newton,  from  the  measurable  data  of  the  move- 
ments of  cosmic  bodies,  deduced  the  celebrated  gravita- 
tion formula,  he  had  to  descend  to  molar — nay,  even  to 
molecular — dimensions,  and  to  express  it  as  a  relation 
referring  to  the  very  elements  of  matter,  before  he  could 
apply  it  in  a  useful  manner :  he  had  to  express  it  as  a 
formula  which  had  reference  to  the  smallest  portions  of 
matter.  In  the  same  way,  the  measurements  made  by 


particulier  de  decouvrir  des  relations 
numeriques  entre  les  quantity's  des 
corps  qui  se  combinent.  Ses  efforts, 
dans  cette  direction,  n'ont  pas  etc" 
egalemeut  heureux  ;  car.  s'il  a  re- 
connu  et  e"nonce  le  premier  la  loi  de 
proportionnalite1  entre  les  quantites 
de  bases  qui  s'unissent  au  meme 
poids  d'acide  et  entre  les  quantites 
d'acides  qui  s'unissent  au  meme 
poids  de  base,  fait  important  et  ex- 
act, il  a  cherche  a  dctnontrer,  d'uri 
autre  cote",  que  ces  quantites  fermai- 
ent  des  series  numeriques  dont  les 
termes  augmentent  suivant  des  re- 
lations simples,  ce  qui  est  errone. 
.  .  .  Ces  erreurs  n'ont  pas  echappe, 
sans  doute,  a  1'attention  des  con- 
temporains  de  Richter  et  ont  con- 
tribue  a  discrediter  ses  travaux. 


.  .  .  Maisnousn'avonspasainsister 
sur  ce  dernier  point.  Relevons, 
dans  1'ccuvre  de  Richter,  les  idees 
justes  et  les  decouvertes  fondamen- 
tales  qui  recouimandent  d'autant 
plus  son  nom  a  1'attention  recon- 
naissante  de  la  posterite  qu'il  est 
demeure  mecounu  et  presque  ignore" 
de  son  temps  "  (Wurtz, '  La  The"orie 
atomique,"  7me  ed.,  1893,  p.  9,  &c.) 
"  L'opposition  meme,  qu'il  profes- 
sait  pour  les  doctrines  du  reforma- 
teur  [Lavoisier]  semble  avoir  con- 
tribue  a  discrediter  les  travaux  de 
Richter :  son  heure  n'etait  pas 
venue  ;  1'inteYet  etait  ailleurs,  et 
en  Allemagne,  comme  en  France  et 
en  Angleterre,  les  esprits  e'taient 
entraines  par  le  courant  des  idees 
nouvelles "  (ibid.,  p.  13). 


THE   ATOMIC   VIEW    OF   NATURE.  395 

many  chemists  previous  to  Dalton  had  to  be  interpreted 
as  referring  not  only  to  such  quantities  as  the  balance 
could  determine,  but  to  the  very  smallest  immeasurable 
particles  of  which  chemical  substances  consist.  For 
this  purpose  Dalton  adopted  what  was  known  as  the 
atomic  view  of  matter.  The  conception  of  matter  as 
made  up  of  independent  particles,  which  for  our  means 
and  methods  prove  not  only  indestructible  but  likewise 
indivisible,  was  revived  as  the  ancient  theory  of  attraction 
had  been.  Combined  with  the  Newtonian  view  that 
weight  is  a  universal  property  of  all  matter,  it  made  the 
two  fundamental  rules  of  chemical  action  intelligible : 
the  two  facts — first,  that  the  total  weight  of  substances 
remains  always  the  same,  be  they  combined  in  ever  so 
many  different  ways ;  and  secondly,  that  all  substances, 
be  they  in  large  or  in  small  quantities,  combine  with  each 
other,  or  separate  from  each  other,  in  definite  and  fixed 
proportions.  This  view  could  not  be  consistently  main- 
tained, except  it  was  referred  to  the  smallest  particles 
into  which  matter  is  practically  divisible :  the  figures 
expressing  the  combining  numbers  were  viewed  by  Dalton 
as  representing  the  relative  weights  of  the  actual  atoms 
or  elements  of  matter.  That  the  ultimate  particles  of 
matter  have  definite  weights  is  the  reason  why  substances 
combine  in  fixed  proportions,  and  why  the  combining 
weight  of  the  compound  is  the  sum  of  the  combining 
weights  of  the  constituents. 

As  the  gravitation  formula  had  given  rise  to  a  sur- 
prising activity  in  physical  astronomy,  to  a  long  series 
of  exact  measurements,  and  to  theoretical  deductions  of  a 
purely  mathematical  kind,  so  the  atomic  theory  of  Dalton 


396  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

in  the  early  years  of  the  century  fixed  the  task  of  chemists 
for  a  long  time  ahead. 

To  begin  with,  an  enormous  amount  of  work  had  to 

be  done  in  determining  the  actual  proportions  in  which 

elementary  substances  combine.     A  very  large  share  of 

9.        this  work  belongs  to  Berzelius,  who  by  a  great  number 

Berzelius. 

of  very  accurate  determinations  confirmed  inductively 
the  correctness  of  Dalton's  theory.  And  even  more  im- 
portant than  the  conformation  of  the  theory  was  the  great 
harvest  of  actual  knowledge  of  the  things  and  processes 
of  nature  which  was  collaterally  gathered,  whilst  chemists 
were  trying  to  prove  or  to  refute  existing  opinions. 

Indeed,  whilst  the  atomic  theory  of  Dalton  was  the 
first  step  towards  a  systematic  and  comprehensive  study 
of  chemical  phenomena — i.e.,  of  the  qualitative  varieties 
under  which  matter  presents  itself  to  us  on  the  surface 
of  this  globe — the  extension  which  was  gained  in  the 
domain  of  actual  facts  was  much  greater  than  the  simpli- 
fication which  the  theory  had  attempted  to  give.  The 
number  of  elements  or  simple  bodies,  which  in  Lavoisier's 
time  hardly  exceeded  thirty,  increased  before  the  year 
1830  to  more  than  double :  the  number  of  new  compounds, 
unknown  before,  has  probably  never  been  counted.  Com- 
pared with  this  growth  of  actual  knowledge  of  facts,  the 
development  of  the  theory  was  slow  and  uncertain.  The 
view  of  nature  from  the  atomic  point  of  view  marks 
indeed  a  great  contrast  to  that  from  the  astronomical 
ip.  point  of  view.  "We  now  live  about  as  long  after  the 
theory  and  reform  of  chemistiT  through  Lavoisier  and  Dalton  as 

gravitation 

compared.     Laplace  lived   after   the   reform   of  physical   astronomy 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE.  397 

through  Newton.  But  who  could  compare  the  state  of 
chemistry  at  the  present  day  with  that  of  astronomy  in 
the  age  of  Laplace  ?  There,  every  step  had  tended  to 
show  that  the  one  Newtonian  formula  sufficed  to  com- 
prehend all  cosmic  phenomena ;  here,  the  simplification 
introduced  by  Dalton  has  had  to  give  way  to  a  series 
of  modifications  which  have  rendered  the  atomic  theory 
one  of  the  most  complicated  machineries  ever  introduced 
into  science.  Let  us  review  in  brief  the  fate  of  Dalton's 
hypothesis  during  the  century  which  followed.  Quite  in 
the  early  years  of  the  atomic  theory,  Wollaston  propheti-  n. 
cally  foretold  that  if  once  an  accurate  knowledge  were  prophecy, 
gained  of  the  relative  weights  of  elementary  atoms,  philo- 
sophers would  not  rest  satisfied  with  the  determination 
of  mere  numbers,  but  would  have  to  gain  a  geometrical 
conception  of  how  the  elementary  particles  were  placed 
in  space.  Van't  Hoff  s  '  La  Chimie  dans  1'Espace ' — pub- 
lished at  Rotterdam  in  1875 — was  the  first  practical  reali- 
sation of  this  prophecy.  Many  stages  had  to  be  gone 
through  before  this  latest  phase  of  the  atomic  view  was 
attained.  Had  it  been  the  case  that  every  elementary  sub- 
stance combines  with  any  other  substance  only  in  one 
fixed  numerical  proportion,  no  necessity  would  have  ex- 
isted to  look  upon  the  atomic  numbers  as  anything  else 
than  equivalents.  But  it  was  found  that  though  the 
combining  numbers  were  fixed  they  were  not  always  the 
same ;  it  was  found  that  if  a  substance  combined  in  two 
or  more  proportions  with  any  other,  the  larger  proportions 
were  always  exact  multiples  of  the  smallest  proportion. 
And  this — the  rule  or  law  of  multiple  proportions — was 


398 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


12. 

Rule  of 

multiple 

proportions. 


exactly  what  gave  to  Dalton's  view  its  great  plausibility,1 
for  if  the  elementary  atom  of  each  substance  had  a  definite 
weight,  it  might  be  that  not  one  atom  only  combined  with 
one  other,  but  that  one  combined  with  two,  or  two  with 
three,  and  so  on.  Indeed  it  was  soon  found  that  this  was 


1  The  different  factors  of  thought 
which  combined  to  give  the  atomic 
theory  that  definiteness  and  useful- 
ness which  it  attained  through  and 
since  Dalton  lay  ready-made  before 
him  ;  but  no  one  had  seen  so  clearly 
as  he  did  how  to  combine  them. 
Proust  had  taught  how  to  distin- 
guish between  chemical  compounds 
and  mixtures.  When  he  prepared 
carbonate  of  copper  artificially,  he 
found  that  it  had  the  same  com- 
position as  the  mineral  which  he 
found  in  nature.  Richter  had 
shown  that  definite  proportions  de- 
scribe the  quantities  in  which  acids 
and  bases  exist  in  neutral  salts. 
Fischer  had  attached  to  his  transla- 
tion of  Berthollet's  work  the  first 
table  of  equivalent  quantities  of 
bases  and  acids  which  combine  to 
neutralise  each  other.  Richter,  and 
after  him  Gay-Lussac,  had  also 
found  that  the  quantities  of  dif- 
ferent metals  which  dissolve  in  the 
same  quantity  of  acid  to  form 
saturated  solutions  combine  also 
with  the  same  weights  of  oxygen 
to  form  oxides.  Richter,  and  after 
him  Proust,  had  found  that  certain 
metals,  like  iron  and  mercury,  form 
more  than  one  fixed  compound  with 
oxygen,  but  without  perceiving  that 
the  different  quantities  of  oxygen 
in  these  fixed  compounds  stand  in 
simple  proportions  to  each  other. 
So  far  as  the  theoretical  side  is 
concerned,  the  idea  that  bodies 
are  formed  of  distinct  particles — 
the  notion  of  the  ultimate  hetero- 
geneousness  or  discontinuity  of  mat- 
ter— was  not  only  familiar  to  the 
ancients,  but  was  adopted  by  many 
physicists  before  Dalton ;  though  the 


chemical  specialists  who  prepared 
the  way  for  Dalton  do  not  seem  to 
have  made  use  of  this  idea.  Boer- 
haave,  and  before  him  Boyle,  had 
spoken  of  atoms  and  of  the  massulce 
or  particles.  Theories  were  not 
wanting  that  these  ultimate  par- 
ticles differed  in  size  and  form,  nor 
the  opposite  view,  that  the  par- 
ticles which  combined  had  the  same 
weight.  The  latter  was  the  view 
of  Higgins,  in  the  exposition  of 
which  (1790)  he  entangled  himself 
in  contradictious,  losing  his  chance 
of  being  one  of  the  founders  of  the 
atomic  theory.  As  Wurtz  and  Kopp 
and  others  who  have  carefully  in- 
vestigated the  rival  claims  have 
said  :  This  honour  of  founding  the 
atomic  theory  belongs  undividedly 
to  Dalton.  It  seems  important  to 
notice  that  his  experiments  with 
mixtures  of  gases,  which  must  have 
begun  about  1790,  impressed  upon 
him  the  idea  that  different  gases 
could  exist  independently  of  each 
other  in  the  same  space,  suggesting 
the  conception  that  neither  of  them 
filled  the  whole  space,  but  that 
they  consisted  of  discontinuous  par- 
ticles. He  himself  refers  to  these 
first  investigations  as  containing 
the  germ  of  his  later  opinions.  It 
must,  however,  be  borne  in  mind 
that  Dalton  was  only  imperfectly 
acquainted  with  the  writings  of 
contemporary  —  especially  Conti- 
nental— writers,  and  that  he  had 
a  wholesome  distrust  for  state- 
ments of  facts  which  he  had  not 
verified  or  observed  himself.  All 
this  is  very  clearly  stated  in  Kopp's 
'  Entwickeluug  der  Chemie,'  p.  285, 
&c. 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


399 


actually  the  case.  The  lowest  number  according  to  which 
any  substance  entered  into  combination  with  any  other 
was  called  the  atomic  weight  or  equivalent. 

There  was,  so  far,  no  necessity  to  look  upon  atomic 
weights  as  anything  else  than  numbers  fixing  a  propor- 
tion. The  unit  could  be  selected  arbitrarily.  It  was  not 
long  before  that  element,  hydrogen,  which  entered  into 
compounds  in  the  relatively  smallest  weight  was  taken  as 
an  arbitrary  unit,  and  all  other  elements  and  compounds  is. 

Equivalents. 

were  tabulated  according  to  the  relative  amount  of  their 
weights  required  to  form  compounds  with  hydrogen  or 
with  any  other  element — e.g.,  oxygen — the  equivalent  of 
which  with  hydrogen  was  known.1 


1  For  many  years  after  the  enun- 
ciation of  the  atomic  theory  great 
uncertainty  and  much  difference 
of  opinion  existed  on  this  and 
other  points.  The  man  who  did 
most  to  elaborate  the  edifice  of 
which  Dalton  had  laid  the  founda- 
tions, who  filled  in  the  outlines  and 
invented  the  language  of  chemistry, 
was  Berzelius.  He  proceeded  in- 
ductively and  gathered  materials 
from  all '  sides  ;  to  him  are  also 
owing  the  greatest  number  of  ac- 
curate analyses,  especially  of  inor- 
ganic substances.  When  he  began 
his  labours  he  was  favourably  dis- 
posed towards  Dalton's  hypothesis ; 
he  clearly  saw  its  capabilities,  but  also 
that  it  was  based  only  upon  a  happy 
suggestion,  that  it  was  introduced 
more  by  deductive  than  by  induc- 
tive reasoning,  and  that  it  needed 
to  be  exhaustively  tested  and  veri- 
fied. After  ten  years,  during  which 
he  published  in  Gilbert's  '  Annalen  ' 
and  in  Thomson's  'Annals  of  Philo- 
sophy' many  series  of  investigations, 
he  was  able  in  1818  to  publish,  in 
his  '  Essay  on  Chemical  Proportions 
and  on  the  Chemical  Effects  of 


Electricity '  (French  translation, 
1819  ;  German  translation,  1820), 
the  first  systematic  and  complete 
exposition  of  the  atomic  theory. 
The  beginning  of  a  really  exact 
treatment  of  chemistry  has  been 
dated  by  H.  Rose,  the  greatest  an- 
alytical chemist  of  the  century,  from 
this  year  1818 — the  year  in  which 
Dalton's  hypothesis  was  proved 
and  generally  accepted.  Others 
have  dated  the  beginning  from 
1808,  when  Dalton  published  his 
theory ;  others  again  from  1776, 
when  Lavoisier  destroyed  the  older 
phlogiston  theory  and  appealed  to 
the  balance ;  others  again  from 
Black's  discovery  of  latent  heat  in 
1760.  In  an  international  history 
of"  thought  it  is  not  of  much  in- 
terest to  decide  whose  claims  to  be 
the  founder  of  modern  chemistrj- 
as  a  science  are  best  established. 
Every  one  of  these  dates  marks  an 
epoch  in  the  advance  of  an  im- 
portant and  independent  branch  of 
research.  Black  took  an  important 
step  in  the  foundation  of  physical 
chemistry  through  his  introduction 
of  the  conception  of  the  quantity 


400  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

A  great  door  was  now  opened,  not  only  for  actual 
observation  and  research,  but  also  for  speculation — i.e., 
for  abstract  thought.  Some  substances,  if  they  entered 
into  combination  with  hydrogen,  required  more  than  one 
unit  of  hydrogen,  and  it  might  therefore  be  that  the  pro- 
portion of  the  combining  weight  of  hydrogen  with  any 
substance  did  not  correctly  give  the  atomic  weight  of  the 
latter,  but  merely  a  multiple  or  sub-multiple  of  it.  Thus, 
assuming  oxygen  combined  with  hydrogen  in  the  propor- 
tion of  8  parts  of  the  former  to  1  part  of  the  latter,  a 
possibility  was  that  the  proportion  might  more  correctly 
be  written  16  to  2  than  8  to  1.  Then,  again,  were  the 
equivalent  or  atomic  weights  necessarily  whole  numbers  ? 
Were  combinations  all  binary,  such  as  acids  and  alkalies 
forming  salts  ?  and  were  more  complex  compounds  resolv- 
able into  binary  compounds  of  simpler  binary  compounds  ? 
Further,  assuming  the  proportions  fixing  the  combining 
weights  to  be  known,  how  did  the  volumes  of  bodies  com- 
bine?— was  there  a  rule  of  volumes  as  there  was  of  weights? 
and  lastly,  what  was  the  reason  or  cause  which  made  sub- 
stances change  their  combinations,  forming  new  ones,  what 
did  chemical  affinity  consist  in,  what  did  it  depend  on, 
how  could  it  be  defined  and  measured  ? 

Considering  that  we  have  to  do  with  a  large  number  of 
independent,  apparently  unchangeable,  elements,  entering 
into  many  thousands  of  differing  compounds,  the  task  of 

of  heat.  Lavoisier  led  the  way  in 
the  development  of  the  purely  arith- 
metical department  of  chemistry, 
in  the  exclusive  study  of  which 
physical  chemistry  was  greatly 
neglected.  Dalton  suggested  a 
formula  which  lent  itself  admir- 
ably to  the  representation  of  these 


purely  arithmetical  relations,  and 
Berzelius  elaborated  this  and  in- 
vented a  practical  nomenclature. 
Black  and  Dalton  threw  out  novel 
ideas  ;  Lavoisier  and  Berzelius  ela- 
borated great  systems  and  created 
great  schools  which  numbered  many 
converts  and  industrious  workers. 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE.       401 

the  chemist  was  enormous,  offering  a  large,  almost  limit- 
less, field  of  research  and  speculation.  Let  us  see  under 
what  leading  ideas  this  knowledge  has  been  arranged. 

In  the  gradual  development  and  clearer  definition  of 
these  conceptions  a  general  rule  of  thought  seems  to 
have  unconsciously  guided  philosophers  probably  more 
than  in  any  other  department  of  knowledge.  It  is  the 
rule  of  simplicity.1  How  the  human  mind  should  have  H. 

"  Simplex 

arrived  at  the  old  formula  of  "  simplex  sigillum  veri "  is  sigiiium 

veri." 

difficult  to  understand  on  any  other  ground  than  that  of 
convenience  and  expediency.  The  prevailing  impression, 
indeed,  which  the  world  of  phenomena  makes  on  the  mind 
of  an  unbiassed  observer  must  be  the  very  reverse  of  sim- 
plicity or  unity  of  law  and  purpose.  That,  nevertheless, 
the  knowledge  of  some  simple  relations  in  time,  number, 
and  space  would  enable  the  human  intellect  to  acquire  a 
considerable  insight  into  the  course  of  events  and  the 
order  of  Nature's  processes  must  have  come  to  philosophers 


1  The  progress'of  chemical  theory  !  notion  of  a  molecule,  an  assemblage 

is   the   history  of   the  attempt  to  [  of  atoms ;  the  conception  of  elemen- 

find  simple  relations  of  number  and  i  tary  bodies  had  to  be  amplified  by 

form,    representing    the    countless  that    of    compound    elements    or 


combinations  of  elementary  sub- 
stances ;  and  of  the  growing  con- 
viction that  nearly  every  simpli- 
fication must,  in  course  of  time, 
be  abandoned.  No  formula  remains 


radicles  ;  the  idea  that  the  atomic 
weights  were  multiples  of  a  lowest 
number  had  to  be  abandoned ;  the 
binary  theory  of  the  combination 
of  bodies  was  replaced  by  the  theory 


unchallenged  except  the  doctrine  of  of  radicles,  of  nuclei,  of  types  ;  the 

fixed  and  fixed  multiple  proportions,  j   simple   nature   of    the   elementary 

and  that  only  if  we  confine   our-  ,   particles    had    to    give    way    to    a 

selves  to  solid  compounds ;  but  the  complicated  atomicity,  from  which 

proportions  themselves  are  not  ac-  there  had  to  be  again  distinguished 

curately  known,  though  no  pheno-  the  valency  or  capacity  of  satura- 

menon  exists  which  disproves  the  tion   of    the    elementary   constitu- 

assumption  that  they  are  invariable.  |   ents.     It  is  a  progress  from  simpler 

The  original  conception  of  the  atom  to  more  and  more  complex  methods 

as  a  round  hard  body  had  to  be  of  representation, 
abandoned  for  the  more  complicated 

VOL.  I.  2  C 


402  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

as  a  kind  of  revelation,  and  it  is  not  surprising  that  it 
came  late  in  the  course  of  civilisation.1 

Nothing  can  have  tended  more  in  this  direction  than 
the  success  of  the  Newtonian  gravitation  formula,  and  of 
the  simple  laws  of  motion,  which,  at  the  time  of  the  birth 
of  modern  chemistry,  stood  firmly  established  as  the  key 
to  all  problems  of  physical  astronomy.  No  wonder  that 
men  were  on  the  look-out  for  correspondingly  simple — 
perhaps  analogous — relations  in  the  world  of  molecular 
phenomena.  One  of  the  earliest  suggestions,  which  came 
forward  soon  after  Dalton's  atomic  view  had  helped  to 
establish  the  prevailing  rule  of  fixed  and  of  multiple  pro- 
portions in  the  chemical  combinations  and  reactions  of 
matter,  was  the  idea  that,  as  to  each  element  belonged  a 
definite  combining  number,  all  these  numbers  must  be  the 
multiple  of  the  lowest  among  them,  the  equivalent  or 
is.  atomic  weight  of  hydrogen.  This  is  Front's  celebrated 

Prout's 

hypothesis,  hypothesis,  which  had  some  ardent  admirers,  and  which 
has  been  repeatedly  abandoned  and  revived  in  the  course 
of  this  century.2  It  is  hardly  possible  to  maintain  it  any 
longer,  since  the  accurate  and  elaborate  measurements  of 

1  Except  indeed  the  Pythagorean   |  processes   at    our   command    could 
notions  are  regarded  as  an  anticipa-   j  not  be  broken  up.     This  primary 
tion  of  it.  substance    might    then    be    either 

2  The  hypothesis  of  Prout,  pub-  hydrogen,  the  lightest  in  weight  of 
lished   anonymously  in   1815,    and   ;  known   substances,  or  some   other 
warmly  defended  by  Thomson,  has   j  substance  of  which  hydrogen  itself 
been  again  and  again  revived.    From   j  was  an  atomic  multiple.     Abroad, 
the  beginning  it  was  put  forward   j  Prout's   hypothesis   was   disproved 
together  with  the  suggestion  that   \  by  Berzelius's  accurate  determine- 


the  different  elementary  substances 
might  after  all  turn  out  to  be  all 
derived  from  one  and  the  same 


tions,  in  England  by  Turner's,  and 
about  1830  it  fell  into  oblivion.  It 
was  again  revived  in  1840  by  Dumas, 


primary  form  of  matter,  and  that  who,  as  well  as  his  followers,  Lau- 
the  atoms  of  this  might  in  the  j  rent  and  Gerhardt,  favoured  the 
atoms  of  our  present  elements  '.  idea  that  the  explanation  of  the 
merely  be  aggregated  in  different  different  properties  of  chemical  corn- 
numbers  and  figures,  held  together  |  pounds,  notably  organic  compounds, 
by  forces,  which  by  the  means  and  ;  was  to  be  found  in  the  arrangement 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


403 


Stas,  who  began  with  a  belief  in  the  hypothesis,  led  to  the 
result  "that  the  simplicity  supposed  by  Front's  hypothesis 
to  exist  in  the  ratios  of  weights  which  come  into  play  in 
chemical  processes  has  experimentally  not  been  found ;  it 
does  not  exist  in  reality." * 

science,  waiting  to  take  a  further 
and  more  definite  development.  It 
is  important  to  keep  before  men's 
minds  the  idea  of  the  genesis  of  the 
elements ;  this  gives  some  form  to 
our  conceptions,  and  accustoms  the 
mind  to  look  for  some  physical  pro- 
duction of  atoms."  Further  on  he 
coins  the  word  "  protyle "  (from 
irpc&rrj  and  SA.TJ)  to  denote  the  original 
kind  of  matter,  and  thus  reminds  us 
that,  though  speculations  of  this 
nature  are  not  infrequent  in  English 
philosophy  since  Roger  Bacon,  the 
English  language  has  no  word  to 
denote  what  the  Germans  call 
"  Urstoff,"  the  Romans  "prima 
materia,"  the  Greeks  rb  oToixtioi'  or 
simply  v\rj.  The  line  of  thought 
which  again  and  again  leads  philo- 
sophers to  speculate  on  this  "  prima 
materia "  and  upon  a  hypothesis 
similar  to  that  of  Prout  is  interest- 
ing and  noteworthy,  though  it  must 
be  acknowledged  that,  so  far,  no 
real  scientific  benefit  has  been  de- 
rived from  it,  and  that  it  rather 
tends  to  upset  the  only  firm  founda- 
tion of  modern  chemistry,  the  fixity 
of  the  equivalent  proportions  as  we 
now  use  and  know  them.  Mende- 
leeff  himself,  in  his  excellent  Fara- 
day lecture  on  the  periodic  law 
('Journal  of  the  Chemical  Society,' 
1889,  p.  634,  &c.)  distinctly  refuses 
to  recognise  any  connection  between 
the  periodic  law  and  the  idea  of  an 
unique  matter. 

1  Stas,  quoted  by  Ostwald, 
'  Lehrbuch  der  Allgemeinen  Chemie,' 
vol.  i.  2nd  ed.,  Leipzig,  1891,  p.  129. 
The  revival  of  the  hypothesis  of 
Prout  about  the  middle  of  the  cen- 
tury was  owing  to  the  discovery  by 
Dumas  and  Stas  of  the  fact  that 
Berzelius's  figure,  12 '20,  for  the 


of  the  elementary  atoms,  in  the 
structure  rather  than  in  the  material 
difference  of  the  elements  them- 
selves. The  development  of  this 
view  in  the  modern  chemistry  of 
"types"  and  "structures"  will 
always  go  hand  in  hand  with  an 
avowed  or  tacit  belief  in  the  exist- 
ence of  an  ultimate  uniformity  of 
substance,  out  of  which  by  a  diver- 
sity of  configuration  of  atoms  the 
infinite  variety  of  compounds  is 
produced.  The  accurate  measure- 
ments of  Stas  had  again  about  the 
year  1860  disproved  the  hypothesis 
of  Prout.  It  has,  however,  again 
turned  up  in  recent  scientific  litera- 
ture. The  theories  of  evolution, 
physical  and  philosophical,  the  dis- 
coveries of  the  spectroscope  regard- 
ing the  small  number  of  elements 
contained  in  the  photosphere  of  the 
sun,  the  periodic  laws  of  Lothar 
Meyer  and  Mendele"eff  and  the 
stereometric  theory  of  the  carbon- 
compounds,  of  which  I  shall  speak 
later  on,  all  point  to  the  con- 
clusion that  our  so-called  elements 
are  composite  bodies,  and  favour  a 
view,  similar  to  that  of  Prout,  that 
possibly  a  single  kind  of  matter 
may  form  the  only  substance  of 
which  atoms,  molecules,  elements, 
and  compounds  are  made  up.  Pro- 
fessor Crookes  in  his  address  to  the 
chemical  section  of  the  British 
Association  in  1886  revived  inter- 
est in  the  subject.  After  quot- 
ing a  variety  of  authorities,  he 
sums  up:  "From  these  passages, 
which  might  easily  be  multiplied, 
it  plainly  appears  that  the  notion — 
not  necessarily  of  the  decomposi- 
bility,  but  at  any  rate  of  the  com- 
plexibility  of  our  supposed  elements 
— is,  so  to  speak,  in  the  air  of 


404  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

Prout's  simple  but  incorrect  assumption  belongs  to  the 
age  which  witnessed  the  decomposition  of  many  com- 
pounds into  their  two  constituents  by  Davy's  successful 
use  of  the  galvanic  battery,  at  the  poles  of  which  the 
two  elements  of  substances  made  their  separate  appear- 
ance. Substances  which  had  always  been  considered 
as  elemental  and  permanent,  such  as  many  oxides  and 
earths,  came  to  be  ranged  among  the  list  of  binary  com- 
pounds. This  lent  plausibility  to  the  idea  that  even  the 
supposed  elements  themselves  might  ultimately  prove  to 
be  aggregates — differing  in  number  and  figure — of  the 
elementary  particles  of  one  and  the  same  primary  sub- 
stance. Though  with  Prout's  hypothesis  this  view  has 
been  repeatedly  held  and  refuted,  another  theory — recom- 
mended likewise  by  its  simplicity — had  its  origin  in  the 
discoveries  of  Davy,  and  the  further  development  of  them 
by  Berzelius.  This  is  the  so-called  electro-chemical  or 
binary  theory  of  chemical  compounds.  The  dual  combina- 
tion of  one  elementary  substance  with  another,  and  again 
of  two  dual  compounds  with  each  other,  and  so  on, 
even  to  the  most  complicated  compounds,  was  to  be  the 
simple  type  of  chemical  combination.  This  view,  so 


atomic  weight  of  carbon,  taking  called  laws  of  phenomena.  This 
oxygen  as  16,  was  incorrect.  An  consideration,  so  familiar  to  astron- 
accourit  of  the  long  series  of  deter-  omers,  was,  I  believe,  quite  over- 
minations  of  this  important  con-  j  looked  in  many  of  the  best  haud- 
stant  will  be  found  in  the  same  !  books  during  the  earlier  half  of  our 
work,  p.  82,  &c.  I  believe  that  in  century,  and  it  is  even  yet  hardly 
the  first  edition  of  this  work  will  touched  upon  in  the  ordinary  text- 
books. The  result  is  an  entirely 
erroneous  impression  produced  on 
the  popular  mind  as  to  the  degree 
of  certainty  which  belongs  to 


also  be  found  the  first  consistent 
attempt  to  introduce  into  chemical 
data  an  estimate  of  the  degree  of 
accuracy  or  the  amount  of  error 
which  attaches  to  our  knowledge  of 
the  constants  of  nature  and  the  so- 


scientific  statements. 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


405 


simple  and  plausible,  governed  research  for  a  long  period, 
but  has  finally  been  abandoned  as  insufficient.1 

Another  blow  was  dealt  at  the  simple  theory  by  which  Discovery  of 


isonmnsin. 


1  The  electro-chemical  theory  of 
Davy  and  Berzelius  was,  after  about 
fifteen  years  of  development,  during 
which  period  the  use  of  the  signifi- 
cant terms  electro  -  positive  and 
electro-negative  was  not  consistent, 
finally  enunciated  by  Berzelius  in 
1818  in  his  '  Essay  on  the  theory  of 
Chemical  Proportions  and  on  the 
Chemical  Action  of  Electricity.' 
From  that  time  it  reigned  almost 
supreme  for  twenty  years,  when 
both  physical  and  chemical  dis- 
coveries began  to  show  its  insuffici- 
ency. A  very  concise  account  of  it 
is  given  in  Kopp's  '  Entwickeluug 
der  Chemie,'  and  in  E.  von  Meyer;s 
'  History  of  Chemistry,'  translated 
by  M'Gowan  (Macmillan  &  Co., 
1891).  Berzelius  clung  to  it  to  the 
last,  and  at  the  present  moment 
there'  exists  a  widespread  opinion 
that  the  future  will  see  a  revival 
and  modified  acceptance  of  the 
Davy  -  Berzelius  theory.  In  rela- 
tion to  this  Helmholtz's  celebrated 
Faraday  kcture  of  the  year  1881 
should  be  read  (see  the  reprint  in 
Helmholtz's  'Vortrage  und  Reden,' 
vol.  ii. )  The  peculiarity  of  the  elec- 
tro-chemical theory  was  that  it  was 
an  atomic  theory  as  well  as  a  theory 
of  chemical  affinity.  When  it  was 
abandoned,  the  two  distinct  in- 
terests, that  of  developing  the 
atomic  view,  so  as  to  give  a  correct 
description  of  the  constitution  of 
chemical  compounds  and  reactions, 
and  that  of  giving  an  explanation 
of  chemical  affinity,  fell  for  a  time 
asunder.  The  former  interest  pre- 
ponderated, owing  mainly  to  two 
reasons,  the  one  theoretical,  the 
other  practical.  The  theoretical 
reason  was  the  need  of  a  different 
method  of  systematically  arranging 
the  chaos  of  new  organic  compounds 


with  which  chemistry  became 
crowded  about  the  year  184.0. 
Berzelius  had  created  the  nomen- 
clature and  notation  of  chemistry  ; 
but  this  proved  insufficient  to  de- 
scribe and  grasp  the  processes  and 
products  of  the  many  carbon  com- 
pounds. The  practical  reason  which 
cast  into  the  background  the  study 
of  chemical  affinity  and  its  nature 
was  the  growing  demands  of  manu- 
facturing chemistry.  This  was 
during  a  long  period  occupied 
mainly  with  the  analysis  and  syn- 
thesis of  new  products,  or  with  new 
and  simpler  methods  for  producing 
well-known  compounds.  The  study 
of  reactions  and  of  the  products  of 
bodies  was  practically  of  more  in- 
terest than  that  of  the  forces  which 
governed  them.  The  question  of 
the  cost  of  producing  chemical  pro- 
ducts was  for  a  long  time  a  second- 
ary one.  Towards  the  end  of  our 
century  both  theoretical  and  prac- 
tical considerations  forced  upon 
chemists  the  necessity  of  making 
themselves  acquainted  with  the 
different  forms  of  energy  which  are 
at  our  command  in  chemical  as  well 
as  in  mechanical  operations,  and 
this  has  led  to  a  renewal  of  the 
study  of  chemical  and  mechanical 
energy,  and  of  the  nature  and  laws 
of  chemical  affinity.  Economy  in 
practical  chemistry  can  be  divided 
into  two  branches  :  the  economy  of 
materials  and  the  economy  of 
energy.  The  great  developments 
in  the  course  of  this  century  have 
consisted  largely  in  utilising  by- 
products and  in  avoiding  waste  of 
substance.  We  are  now  only  ap- 
proaching the  second  problem  : 
how  to  put  the  energy  which  is  at 
our  command  to  the  best  use. 


406  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

Berzelius  united  Dalton's  and  Davy's  researches  into  a 
comprehensive  system  of  chemistry.  The  identity  or 
difference  of  chemical  substances  seemed  in  the  early  part 
of  the  century  to  be  fixed  by  the  constituent  elements  and 
their  quantitative  proportions  determined  by  a  qualitative 
and  quantitative  analysis.  This  simple  view  had  to  be 
abandoned  when  Wohler  in  1823,  Liebig  in  1824,  and 
Faraday  in  1825  found  that  entirely  different  qualities, 
indicating  a  different  constitution,  could  belong  to  bodies 
having  the  same  elements  in  the  same  numerical  propor- 
tions.1 The  composition  of  a  compound  had  to  be  dis- 
tinguished from  its  constitution,  the  elementary  from  the 
constituent  analysis  and  formula.  It  took  forty  years 
before  the  great  variety  of  views  which  were  brought 
forward  with  the  purpose  of  explaining  how  composition 
and  constitution  of  the  same  aggregate  of  elements  might 

1  This  phenomenon  is  termed  hydrogen,  but  showed  totally  differ- 
"  Isomerism,"  from  the  Greek  word  ent  properties,  such  as  unequal 
iffofifpfis,  which  signifies  "having  density  in  the  gaseous  state.  Two 
equal  parts."  The  term  was  intro-  oxides  of  tin,  having  the  same  com- 
duced  by  Berzelius  in  1830,  after  position,  were  also  known,  and  two 
he  had  satisfied  himself  that  com-  modifications  of  •'  phosphoric  acid." 
pounds  existed,  differing  widely  The  explanation  of  these  anomalies 
in  their  properties,  which  contain  caused  Berzelius  much  difficulty, 
the  same  constituent  elements  in  He  resorts  to  the  notion  of  a 
the  same  proportions,  and  which  difference  of  grouping  of  the  con- 
combine  with  other  bodies  in  the  stituent  atoms.  "The  isomerism 
same  proportions  to  form  neutral  of  compounds,"  he  says,  "in  itself 
salts.  This  he  found  to  be  the  case  presupposes  that  the  positions  of 
with  "racemic"  and" tartaric" acid,  the  atoms  in  them  must  be  differ- 
Up  to  that  time  he  had  hesitated  |  ent"  (see  E.  von  Meyer,  'History 
in  accepting  the  growing  evidence  of  Chemistry,'  p.  238).  A.  Rau  in 
that  equal  constituents  in  equal  his  '  Theorien  der  modernen  Chemie' 
proportions  did  not  constitute  (3  parts,  Braunschweig,  1877-84) 
identity  of  compounds.  Wohler  in  gives  in  the  appendix  to  the  third 
1823  and  Liebig  in  1824  had  found  part  a  detailed  history  of  isomerism. 
the  same  numerical  composition  for  He  denies  that  Berzelius  refers  to 
"cyanate"  and  "fulminate"  of  the  different  position  of  atoms  in 
silver.  In  1825  Faraday  found  two  order  to  explain  isomerism  ;  he  at- 
hydrocarbons  which  contained  the  tributes  this  suggestion  to  Dumas 
same  proportions  of  carbon  and  in  1833. 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


407 


differ,  could  be  approximately  brought  into  line  and  order. 
This  period  was  filled  by  the  development  of  the  chem- 
istry of  organic  compounds.  The  chemical  substances  17. 

Organic 

which  make  up  the  framework  and  numerous  tissues  chemistry. 
of  all  living  beings,  the  juices  and  products  of  vegetable, 
the  food  and  the  excreta  of  animal  organisms,  consist 
mostly  of  a  few  elementary  bodies,  combined  according 
to  numbers  which  are  highly  complex  and  unintelligible. 
Most  of  these  compounds,  if  removed  from  the  organism 
which  contained  them,  proved  to  be  subject  to  rapid  de- 
composition. An  increasing  number  of  stable  compounds, 
however,  were  in  course  of  time  prepared  from  these 
residues,  and  these  formed  especially  the  subject  of  organic 
analysis.  Already  Lavoisier  had  indicated  how  some 
system  might  be  brought  into  the  apparent  complexity 
of  these  organic  bodies;  and  this  view  was  adopted  by 
Berzelius  and  incorporated  in  his  dual  or  binary  system.1 


1  Kopp's  account  of  the  develop- 
ment of  Berzelyis's  views  on  organic 
compounds  is  most  interesting  and 
instructive.  As  late  as  1814  he 
could  not  reconcile  the  composition 
of  organic  acids,  such  as  oxalic  acid, 
with  the  atomic  theory  ;  but  re- 
newed efforts  and  improved  methods 
of  analysis  taught  him  in  the  fol- 
J owing  years  how  to  apply  the 
atomic  formula;  to  the  description 
of  such  compounds.  "  He  was 
the  first  to  show  the  only  right 
road  to  inform  ourselves  regarding 
the  constitution  of  these  bodies, 
the  method,  namely,  of  analysing 
their  combinations  with  inorganic 
substances  of  known  atomic  weight. 
.  .  .  He  had  also  a  great  share  in 
establishing  the  view  that  the  ratios 
of  combinations  in  organic  com- 
pounds are  analogous  to  those 
of  inorganic  substances,  and  that 


theories  of  the  former  must  begin 
by  comparing  them  with  the  lat- 
ter "  ('  Geschichte  der  Chemie,'  vol. 
i.  p.  398 ;  cf.  also  '  Die  Entwickel- 
ung  der  Chemie,'  p.  532,  &c.)  To 
Berzelius  is  thus  due  more  than  to 
any  other  man  the  breaking  down 
of  the  barrier  which  had  before  his 
time  divided  the  chemistry  of  or- 
ganic from  that  of  inorganic  sub- 
stances. For  a  considerable  time 
Berzelius  did  not  look  upon  organic 
compounds  as  binary — in  fact,  in 
1814  he  assumed  that  the  difference 
between  organic  and  inorganic  com- 
pounds lay  in  this,  that  the  latter 
were  all  binary,  whereas  the  former 
were  ternary  or  quaternary.  The 
French  chemists,  under  the  influ- 
ence of  Lavoisier's  oxygen  theory, 
favoured  the  binary  view,  and  this 
was  much  strengthened  by  Gay- 
Lussac's  researches  on  cyanogen  (in 


408  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

It  was  supposed  that  the  simple  and  well-knowu  elements 
of  these  bodies  might  have  the  property  of  forming 
primarily  combinations  which  were  more  firmly  knit 
together  than  others,  that  these  primary  combinations 
might  then  as  it  were  take  the  place  of  elements  and 
act  like  them,  forming  with  others  of  similar  constitution, 
or  with  the  simple  elements  themselves,  more  complex 
compounds.  In  these  higher  compounds  they  might 
behave  like  elementary  bodies,  entering  into  and  being 
expelled  from  them  in  their  own  proper  combinations 
without  being  broken  up  into  the  ultimate  elementary 
constituents.  One  of  the  functions  of  the  living  organism 
was  by  the  action  of  the  vital  forces  to  produce  these 
primary  compounds  or  complex  atoms.  It  was  thus 
thought  that  as  inorganic  bodies  were  made  up  of  con- 
stituents which  were  elements,  so  organic  bodies  were 
made  up  of  constituents  which  were  themselves  partly 
compounds.  A  new  term  had  to  be  coined  for  those 
constituents  which  might  comprise  both  elementary 
bodies  and  these  primary  compounds  which  behaved 
like  elements  in  organic  substances.  This  was  the  term 
"  Eadicle."  A  radicle  might  be  an  element  or  a  com- 
pound.1 For  a  long  time  it  was  thought  that  these 


1815),  a  compound  of  carbon  and 
nitrogen,  which  was  shown  to  behave 
like  an  element.  Ampere  in  the 
following  year  showed  how  the  salts 
of  ammonia  could  be  brought  into 
line  with  the  salts  of  other  al- 
kalies by  considering  them  to  con- 
tain a  compound  element  (consist- 
ing of  nitrogen  and  hydrogen)  in 
place  of  a  simple  element.  In  his 
celebrated  essay  of  1818  Berzelius 
defines  organic  acids  as  binary 
compounds  of  oxygen  with  com- 


pound elements  or  radicles  (Kopp, 
'  Geschichte  der  Chemie,'  vol.  iv.  p. 
269). 

1  The  term  "radicle,"  to  desig- 
nate the  principal  constituent  of  a 
compound,  was  used  as  far  back  as 
17S7  in  the  discussions  through 
which  the  French  chemists  reform- 
ed the  nomenclature  of  chemistry 
(Kopp,  '  Geschichte,'  KC.,  vol.  iv. 
p.  266).  It  acquired  a  more  defi- 
nite meaning  about  the  year  1S35, 
when  Liebig,  in  common  with  Ber- 


THE    ATOMIC   VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


409 


complex  radicles,  as  distinguished  from  the  elements, 
were  produced  mainly  —  if  not  exclusively  —  in  the  organ- 
ism of  the  plant  or  of  the  animal.  Liebig  himself,  who  is. 

Liebig's  de- 

fa  voured  this  view,  and  who  first  brought  organic  chem-  fimtionof 

organic 

istry  in  its  application  to  agriculture  and  physiology  Cheim8trv- 
under  the  notice  of  a  large  circle  of  readers,  introduced 
this  branch  of  the  subject  with  the  designation  of  the 
chemistry  of  compound  radicles,  inorganic  or  mineral 
chemistry  being  termed  the  chemistry  of  simple  radicles. 
The  radicles  were,  according  to  Liebig,  the  true  elements 
of  organic  chemistry.  The  binary  system  of  Berzelius 
received  another  attack  led  by  the  celebrated  French 
chemists  Laurent  and  Gerhardt,  with  whom  Dumas  tem- 
porarily allied  himself.  It  was  about  the  year  1840  that 
the  idea  of  "  substitution  "  entered  the  list  of  formulae 
by  which  chemical  philosophers  attempted  to  systematise 
and  simplify  the  ever-growing  number  of  definite  com- 
pounds, supplied  mainly  by  organic  analysis.1  It  was 


19. 

Substitu- 


zelius  and  with  Dumas,  established 
what  is  now  called  the  older  radicle- 
theory  of  organic  compounds.  As 
Kopp  has  shown  ('  Entwickelung 
der  Chemie,  p.  576,  &c.),  it  remained 
undecided  at  that  time  whether 
these  organic  radicles  had  actual 
existence,  or  whether  they  were 
merely  a  convenient  symbolism, — 
whether  they  could  be  isolated,  like 
cyanogen,  or  whether  they  existed 
only  in  combinations,  —  whether 
they  were  fixed  and  unchangeable, 
or  whether  they  could  themselves 
be  converted  one  into  another, — 
whether  the  same  compound  could 
be  referred — for  convenience  sake 
— to  more  than  one  constituent  rad- 
icle. "By  most  chemists  the  defini- 
tion of  organic  chemistry  given  by 
Liebig  ('Organic  Chemistry,'  1843) 


was  adopted,  that  it  was  the  chem- 
istry of  compound  radicles ;  .  .  . 
that  these  radicles  really  existed 
in  the  compounds  as  definite  con- 
stituents ;  and  if  it  was  then  said 
that  these  radicles  were  mostly 
hypothetical,  this  was  understood 
as  meaning  that  some  of  them  were 
known  in  the  free  state,  others  not " 
(p.  581). 

1  Even  before  that  time  the  views 
of  many  eminent  chemists  had  been 
greatly  influenced  by  the  discoveries 
and  experiments  of  two  great  na- 
tural philosophers  of  this  country 
who  kept  themselves  free  from  the 
theoretical  considerations  which  had 
led  Berzelius  in  the  elaboration  of 
his  electro-chemical  and  binary  sys- 
tem. These  were  the  researches  of 
Davy  regarding  the  so-called  hydro- 


410 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


found  that  one  or  more  atoms  in  an  organic  compound, 
notably  of  hydrogen,  might  be  replaced  by  an  equal 
number  of  atoms  of  other  elements,  and  that  such  pro- 
ducts of  substitution  retained  similar  qualities,  and  could 
be  mutually  converted  into  each  other,  the  type  of  the 
compound  remaining  the  same.  The  process  of  substitu- 
tion led  to  the  conception  of  "  Types,"  which  remained 
the  same  whilst  the  individual  compounds  varied  ac- 
cording to  the  different  elements  which  were  introduced. 


gen  acids  of  chlorine,  bromine,  and 
iodine,  and  the  investigations  of 
Graham  into  the  salts  of  phosphoric 
acid  and  its  different  modifications. 
Davy,  though  together  with  Ber- 
zelius  the  founder  of  the  electro- 
chemical theory,  had  found  it  neces- 
sary to  modify  the  oxygen  theory 
of  Lavoisier — viz.,  that  oxygen  was 
necessarily  the  acid  -  forming  ele- 
ment :  he,  and  after  him  Dulong 
in  France,  had  explained  the  so- 
called  oxygen  acids  like  sulphuric 
acid  as  hydrogen  compounds  of 
certain  compound  radicles  (S04) 
exactly  as  hydrochloric  acid  is  a 
hydrogen  acid  of  the  simple  radicle 
chlorine.  Graham's  discovery  of 
three  modifications  of  phosphoric 
acid,  and  of  the  different  power  of 
saturation  of  these  three  modifica- 
tions, led  to  long  discussions  as  to 
what  is  really  meant  by  a  neutral 
salt.  Liebig  in  the  year  1838,  in 
an  important  memoir  gathering  to- 
gether the  conclusions  which  these 
facts,  not  easily  reconciled  with 
Berzelius's  system,  had  led'  him  to, 
emphasised  there  the  twofold  pos- 
sibility of  regarding  metallic  salts 
either  with  Berzelius  as  binary 
combinations  of  oxides  with  an- 
hydrous acids,  or  else  as  products 
of  substitution  of  hydrogen  com- 
pounds, hydrogen  being  replaced 
by  metals.  The  choice  might  then 


depend  on  considerations  of  con- 
venience :  the  one  view  might  be 
more  suitable  for  inorganic — notably 
metallic — compounds,  the  other  for 
organic  compounds.  The  hydrogen 
theory  was  thus  introduced  along- 
side of  the  oxygen  theory  ;  substi- 
tution was  introduced  alongside  of 
simple  combination.  Though  in 
this  stage  the  radicle  theory  was 
already  threatened,  it  was  still  pos- 
sible to  uphold  the  binary  theory, 
though  it  was  not  necessary.  Chlo- 
rine could  act  in  the  same  way  as 
oxygen,  being  an  electro  -  negative 
element.  But  when,  in  pursuing 
the  line  of  investigation  opened  out, 
it  was  found  that  chlorine,  the 
electro-negative  element,  could  take 
the  place  of  hydrogen  in  organic 
compounds  without  changing  their 
chemical  character,  the  binary 
theory,  based  upon  polar  (electri- 
cal) contrasts,  became  insufficient 
as  a  means  of  explanation  or  even 
of  classification.  Dumas  was  the 
first  to  indicate  this  (1834),  though 
he  attempted  to  save  the  electro- 
chemical or  polar  theory  by  stating 
that  the  two  electrically  opposite 
constituents  of  an  organic  com- 
pound might  contain  the  same 
elements  in  the  opposite  electrical 
positions  (Kopp,  '  Entwickelung  der 
Chemie,'  pp.  564,  595,  &c.) 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


411 


Whilst  the  "  Eadicle "  theory  of  Berzelius  and  Liebig 
sought  to  simplify  the  study  of  chemical  compounds  by 
reducing  them  to  a  definite  number  of  complex  atoms,  the 
"  Type  "  theory  of  Laurent  and  Gerhard t  sought  to  attain  20. 

TVDG 

the  same  object  by  establishing  a  small  number  of  simple  theory, 
formulae,  corresponding  to  well-known  simple  substances, 
under  which  the  vast  number  of  organic  compounds  could 
be  grouped.1     The   conception   of   a  "  type "   exhibiting 


1  The  type  theory  was  slowly  and 
hesitatingly  developed.  Dumas, 
whose  researches  about  1835  pre- 
pared the  way,  did  not  himself 
draw  the  immediate  consequences  ; 
this  was  done  by  Laurent,  "  who 
maintained  that  the  structure  and 
chemical  character  of  organic  com- 
pounds are  not  materially  altered 
by  the  entrance  of  chlorine  and  the 
separation  of  hydrogen "  (E.  v. 
Meyer,  '  History  of  Chemistry,'  p. 
261).  Laurent  then  elaborated  his 
theory  of  "Nuclei."  They  remind 
one  of  Berzelius's  and  Liebig's  radi- 
cles. The  nuclei  were  the  ground- 
work of  organic  compounds  ;  they 
were  not  unalterable  as  the  radicles 
had  been  considered  to  be.  Dumas, 
who  at  first  repudiated  Laurent's 
ideas,  was  later  on,  through  his 
own  experimental  discoveries,  led  to 
adopt  similar  views.  The  "  radicle," 
as  the  permanent  constituent  in  or- 
ganic compounds — corresponding  to 
the  elements  in  inorganic  chemistry 
— had  given  way  to  the  changeable 
nucleus,  which  only  preserved  its 
form ;  the  unchangeable  principle 
was  found  in  the  form,  the  structure 
or  type,  instead  of  in  the  substance 
of  the  simple  or  composite  consti- 
tuents. This  led  to  an  extensive 
study  of  the  forms  of  chemical 
compounds — as  expressed  by  their 
formulae,  and  apart  from  the  study 
of  the  properties  of  the  original 
constituents.  Types  were  invented, 


frequently  in  a  somewhat  arbitrary 
manner.  "  The  ultimate  result  was 
that  an  empty  scheme  of  formula- 
tion carried  the  day  over  what  was 
really  good  in  this  doctrine"  (ibid., 
p.  264).  "The  unitary  conception 
was  to  step  into  the  place  of  the 
dualistic.  .  .  .  Every  chemical  com- 
pound forms  a  complete  whole,  and 
cannot  therefore  consist  of  two 
parts.  The  chemical  character  is 
dependent  primarily  upon  the  ar- 
rangement and  number  of  the 
atoms,  and  in  a  lesser  degree  upon 
their  chemical  nature "  (p.  265). 
This  is  the  beginning  of  the  second 
great  step  which  was  taken  in  the 
elaboration  of  the  atomic  view  of 
matter  and  nature.  The  atomic  view 
first  became  a  scientific  instrument, 
when  arithmetical  relations  of  a 
definite  and  unalterable  kind  were 
suggested  and  proved  to  exist ;  it 
became  a  yet  more  useful  instru- 
ment, when  to  the  arithmetical 
there  were  added  geometrical  con- 
ceptions. Position,  arrangement, 
and  structure  are  conceptions 
which  involve  ideas  of  distance  and 
space.  It  is  true  that  for  a  long 
time  these  terms  were  used  merely 
symbolically  ;  the  ultimate  conse- 
quences of  such  conceptions  can 
however  not  be  avoided.  The  his- 
tory of  chemical  theory  in  the 
second  half  of  the  nineteenth  cen- 
tury is  a  proof  of  this. 


412  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

certain  stable  qualities  with  a  multitude  of  changing 
varieties  was  a  notion  familiar  to  other  branches  of  natural 
history.  The  idea  of  substituting  one  element  for  another 
gave  the  death-blow  to  the  theory  of  Berzelius,  which 
assumed  that  elements  paired  with  each  other,  according 
to  some  polar  contrast.  It  was  found,  for  instance,  that 
the  element  chlorine,  which  stood  on  one  side  of  the 
scale — the  electro-negative — could  take  the  place  of  the 
opposite  electro-positive  element  hydrogen. 

In  the  course  of  time  the  conception  of  types  was  much 
changed,  and  became  more  and  more  complicated ;  it  had 
however  the  effect  of  finally  destroying  the  binary  view  of 
chemical  composition,  and  restoring  in  its  place  the  older 
unitary  conception. 

All  these  attempts  to  simplify  the  study  of  chemical 
compounds,  by  reducing  them  to  simple  or  complex  ele- 
ments, or  to  pairs  of  simpler  combinations,  or  by  ranging 
them  according  to  types,  were  useful  in  many  ways  in 
extending  the  knowledge  of  bodies,  in  indicating  new 
methods  of  inquiry,  and  in  suggesting  instructive  experi- 
ments : l  none  of  them  were  universally  accepted  in  the 


1  About  that  time  —  so  far  as 
chemistry  proper,  i.e.,  the  study  of 
compounds  and  of  reactions  was 
concerned — there  existed  two  main 
currents  of  thought,  the  most  illus- 
trious and  influential  representa- 
tives of  which  were  Kekule  (1829- 
96,  first  professor  at  Ghent,  then 
since  1865  at  Bonn),  and  Kolbe 
(1818-1884,  first  professor  at  Mar- 
burg, then  since  1865  at  Leipsic). 


Liebig,  Wohler,  and  Bunsen.  To 
them  as  a  third  can  be  added  the 
name  of  A.  W.  von  Hofmann  (1818- 
1892),  who,  through  his  twenty 
years' residence  in  London,  did  much 
to  introduce  a  knowledge  of  German 
chemistry  and  German  teaching 
methods  in  England,  and  who  from 
1865  established  the  modern  Berlin 
school  of  chemistry.  It  would  be 
impossible  to  enter  here  into  details 


As    teachers    and    centres   of    aca-  !   as  to  how — mainly  through  the  influ- 

demic  influence,   though  in  differ-  ence  of  these  three  men — the  work 

ent,  frequently  opposite  directions.  begun  by  Liebig  and  Wohler  was 

these  two  eminent  men  continued  j   extended,  and  how  especially  also 

the  work   started   in  Germany  by  .   the  great  development  of  chemical 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


413 


middle  of  the  century.1     It  thus  happened  that  a  variety       21. 
of  circumstances  combined  to  bring  into  prominence,  and  in  chemical 

theory  about 

subsequently  into  general  acceptance,  the  modern  view  of  the  middle 

*  of  the  cen- 

tury. 


industry  in  Germany  was  brought 
about ;  a  creation  almost  as  charac- 
teristic of  German  intellect,  and 
probably  more  lastingly  beneficial, 
than  the  political  changes  which 
mark  the  same  period  in  history. 
More  important  for  a  history  of 
Thought  is  it  to  note  how  Kolbe 
attached  himself  to  the  school  of 
Wohler  and  Berzelius,  and  tried  to 
preserve  the  continuity  of  thought 
in  developing  the  fruitful  ideas  con- 
tained in  the  writings  of  the  latter. 
' '  He  united  the  conclusions  from 
his  own  researches  with  the  declin- 
ing theory  of  Berzelius  ;  he  endued 
the  latter  with  new  life  by  throw- 
ing aside  whatever  of  it  was  dead, 
and  replacing  this  by  vigorous 
principles.  From  his  own  and  other 
investigations  he  came  to  the  con- 
clusion that  the  unalterability  of 
radicles,  as  taught  by  Berzelius, 
could  no  longer  be  maintained,  since 
the  facts  of  substitution  had  to  be 
taken  into  account."  He  especially 
developed  Berzelius's  idea  of  paired 
compounds.  (See  E.  v.  Meyer's 
'History  of  Chemistry,'  p.  295.) 
Kolbe's  joint  work  with  Frankland 
was  of  the  greatest  importance  to 
science.  The  influence  of  Kolbe 
was  also  largely  of  a  polemical 
nature,  inasmuch  as  he  and  some 
others,  notably  F.  Mohr  (whose 
name  will  have  to  be  mentioned  in 
a  later  chapter),  protested  energeti- 
cally against  the  formal  character 
of  much  of  the  writings  and  work 
produced  by  the  French  school 
which  opposed  the  views  of  Ber- 
zelius. This  school,  of  which 
Dumas,  Laurent,  and  Gerhardt 
were  the  founders,  and  which 
exerted  a  very  marked  and  beneficial 
influence  through  the  teaching  and 
the  finished  literary  productions  of 


Wurtz  (1817-84),  was  closely  allied 
with  the  school  of  Kekule  in  Ger- 
many, who  indeed  began  by  logi- 
cally developing  Gerhardt's  ideas, 
being  af  terwards  led  to  special  views 
and  methods  of  his  own,  through 
which  he  became  the  real  founder 
of  the  so-called  structural  formulae, 
and  of  the  doctrine  of  the  linking 
of  atoms.  I  must  here  especially 
record  my  indebtedness  to  the  ad- 
mirable historical  essays  of  Wurtz 
('  The"orie  atomique,'  7me  ed.,  1893, 
and  '  History  of  Chemical  Theory,' 
transl.  by  Watts).  For  clearness 
and  elegance  of  style,  they  are 
quite  as  marked  as  are  Kopp's 
historical  works  for  breadth,  im- 
partiality, and  philosophical  in- 
sight. 

1  The  adherents  of  the  theory  of 
substitution  and  types,  sometimes 
called  the  "modern,"  also  the 
"  French,"  school,  urged  against 
the  followers  of  Berzelius,  which 
adhered  to  the  "electro-chemical" 
or  "radicle"  view,  that  since  an 
electro  -  positive  element  could  be 
replaced  by  a  contrary  one,  there 
was  no  sense  in  upholding  the 
polar  difference.  They  pointed  out 
that  organic  substances  were  not 
electrolytic  ;  and  they  criticised  the 
artificial  invention  and  multiplica- 
tion of  new  radicles  which  had  no 
real  existence,  as  arbitrary.  On 
the  other  side,  the  followers  of 
Berzelius  objected  to  the  entire 
ignoring  by  the  new  school  of 
the  really  existing  electro -chemi- 
cal differences,  and  reproved  them 
for  having  destroyed  the  connec- 
tion between  organic  and  inorganic 
chemistry,  and  for  having  intro- 
duced a  purely  formal  systematisa- 
tion  according  to  merely  externa 
differences.  They  rightly  upheld 


414 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


the  "  atomicity  "  or  "  valency  "  of  chemical  substances — 
be  they  elements  or  compounds.  This  most  recent  de- 
velopment of  chemical  systematisation  originated  in  Eng- 
land,1 whereas  the  "  radicle  "  theory  belonged  more  to  the 


the  view  that  an  understanding  of 
chemical  reactions  must  ultimately 
depend  upon  a  study  of  the  nature 
and  degree  of  chemical  affinity,  and 
maintained  that  so  far  the  connec- 
tion of  chemical  with  electrolytic 
phenomena  afforded  the  only  clue 
to  the  comprehension  of  the  nature 
of  chemical  affinity.  The  atomic 
theory  had  now  absorbed  all  in- 
terest, to  the  detriment  of  a  physi- 
cal theory  of  chemical  affinity  such 
as  Berthollet  had  attempted.  It 
was  held  that  by  ignoring  the 
electro  -  chemical  differences,  the 
"  modern ''  school  lost  the  only  re- 
maining chance  of  explaining,  and 
not  merely  classifying,  chemical  phe- 
nomena. A  good  exposition  of  the 
latter  argument  will  be  found  in 
A.  Rau,  'Die  Theorien  der  moder- 
nen  Chemie.' 

1  The  number  is  small  of  the  Eng- 
lish names  which  about  the  middle 
of  this  century  figured  prominently 
in  the  discussions  by  which,  in  the 
German  and  French  annals  of 
science,  correcter  views  on  the  con- 
stitution of  chemical  compounds 
were  gradually  elaborated.  Kane's 
work  was  overlooked,  but  William- 
son, Odling,  and  Frankland  have 
had  a  very  marked  influence  ;  and, 
as  in  so  many  other  sciences,  pioneer 
work  in  modern  chemistry  was  done 
in  this  country,  notably  by  Frank- 
land.  Liebig,  after  his  visit  to 
England  in  1837,  wrote  to  Wonler  : 
li  I  have  traversed  England,  Ireland, 
and  Scotland  in  all  directions,  have 
seen  much  that  is  astonishing,  but 
have  learnt  little  :  whence  is  scien- 
tific knowledge  to  come  in  England, 
as  the  teachers  are  so  inferior '' 
Among  older  men,  Thomson  is  still 
the  _best;  among  younger  men, 


Graham  :  modest  and  unassuming, 
he  makes  the  most  beautiful  dis- 
coveries. Nevertheless,  a  splendid 
nation,"  &c.  &c.  ('Liebig's  und 
Wohler's  Briefwechsel,'  vol.  i.  p. 
113.)  From  what  I  stated  above 
(chapter  iii.  p.  296,  &c.),  we  are, 
however,  quite  prepared  to  find 
that  the  idea  which  more  than  any 
other  has  brought  some  order  and 
system  into  modern  chemical  theory, 
and  which  has  united  the  diverg- 
ing currents  of  the  foreign  schools, 
has  come  from  England.  Frank- 
land  more  than  any  other  must 
be  looked  upon  as  the  origina- 
tor of  the  modern  theory  of  the 
atomicity  or  valency  of  chemical 
elements  and  compounds.  The 
history  of  this  conception  can  be 
well  studied  in  the  collection  of 
scientific  papers  which  he  published 
with  valuable  introductions  in  1877 
('  Experimental  Researches  in  Pure, 
Applied,  and  Physical  Chemistry,' 
London,  van  Voorst).  His  re- 
searches commenced  in  those  years 
when  great  confusion  existed  in  or- 
ganic chemistry,  "when  the  wildest 
theories  of  the  constitution  of  or- 
ganic compounds  created  but  little 
surprise ;  the  assertion,  for  instance, 
that  an  atom  of  carbon  was  united 
with  four  atoms  of  hydrogen  and 
two  of  chlorine  would  scarcely  have 
been  considered  intrinsically  impro- 
bable, and  certainly  not  impossible  " 
(loc.  cit.,  p.  26).  The  idea  existed 
that  bodies  could  enter  into  combin- 
ation with  other  bodies,  notably  or- 
ganic radicles,  and  could  still  retain 
in  such  combination  their  original 
affinities  unimpaired  ;  a  new  term, 
that  of  "conjugate,"  "copulated," 
or  "  paired  "  compounds,  had  been 
invented  and  adopted  by  Berzelius. 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


415 


German,  and  the  "  type  "  theory  to  the  French,  school  of 
chemists.  But  the  idea  of  the  "  atomicity  "  and  "  valency  " 
or  saturating  capacity  of  the  element  of  any  substance  was 
not  possible  without  the  clear  notion  of  the  "  molecule  " 
as  distinct  from  the  "  atom."  This  idea  had  lain  dormant 
in  the  now  celebrated  but  long  forgotten  law  of  Avogadro, 
which  was  established  in  the  year  1811,  almost  immedi- 
ately after  the  appearance  of  Dalton's  atomic  theory. 

The  atomic  theory  may  be  regarded  in  two  distinct 
ways,  and  it  is  instructive  from  the  point  of  view  of  the 
history  of  thought  to  see  how  -these  two  different  aspects 
of  the  theory  have  gradually  presented  themselves.  The 
older  and  vague  atomic  theory  professed  to  be  a  theory  of 
the  constitution  of  bodies,  and  to  afford  the  basis  for  an 
explanation  of  physical  phenomena ;  in  order  to  do  this, 
forces  of  attraction  and  repulsion  between  the  particles  of 


22. 

Two  aspects 
of  the 
atomic 
theory. 


It  appears  that  this  theory  was 
largely  based  upon  a  compound 
prepared  by  Bunsen,  and  called 
' '  cacodyl."  This  compound  was  one 
of  the  few  organic  radicles  which 
contained  a  metal — arsenic.  Frank- 
land,  partly  alone,  partly  in  union 
with  Kolbe,  entered  upon  a  series 
of  researches  which  had  two  distinct 
objects.  Both  these  objects  were 
foreign  to  that  school  which  had 
given  up  the  radicle  theory,  and 
which,  by  looking  upon  organic 
compounds  as  essentially  different 
from  inorganic  compounds,  had  lost 
that  important  clue — the  connec- 
tion of  the  two  branches  of  chemis- 
try. These  objects  were  the  isola- 
tion of  the  so-called  radicles  or 
compound  elements  and  the  pre- 
paration of  other  "  orgauo-metal- 
lic "  bodies.  The  latter  research 
led  to  new  insight  into  the  nature 
of  chemical  combinations.  "  I  had 


not  proceeded  far,"  says  Franklaud, 
"  in  the  investigation  of  the  organo- 
metallic  compounds  before  the  facts 
brought  to  light  began  to  impress 
upon  me  the  existence  of  a  fixity  in 
the  maximum  combining  value  or 
capacity  of  saturation  in  the  metal- 
lic elements  which  had  not  before 
been  suspected.  ...  It  was  evi- 
dent that  the  atoms  of  zinc,  tin, 
arsenic,  antimony,  &c. ,  had  only 
room,  so  to  speak,  for  the  attach- 
ment of  a  fixed  and  definite  number 
of  the  atoms  of  other  elements,  or, 
as  I  should  now  express  it,  of  the 
bonds  of  other  elements.  This 
hypothesis,  which  was  communi- 
cated to  the  Royal  Society  on  May 
10,  1852,  constitutes  the  basis  of 
what  has  since  been  called  the  doc- 
trine of  atomicity  or  equivalence  of 
elements  ;  and  it  was,  so  far  as  I 
am  aware,  the  first  announcement 
of  that  doctrine"  (ibid.,  p.  145). 


416 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


matter  had  to  be  assumed,  and  elaborate  calculations  as  to 
the  integral  or  resultant  effect  of  these  elementary  forces 
had  to  be  instituted,  or  at  least  formulated.  An  interest- 
ing and  typical  case  of  these  attempts  was  the  theory  of 
Boscovich,  referred  to  in  the  last  chapter.1  In  looking 
back  on  the  history  of  science,  it  can  now  be  safely  stated 
that,  ingenious  as  those  theories  were,  they  led  to  no  re- 
sults in  the  direction  of  the  calculation  of  the  molar  and 
molecular  properties  of  bodies,  or  if  they  did,  they  yielded 
none  which  could  not  be  gained  by  the  opposite  view  which 
regarded  matter  as  continuous.  The  atomic  theory,  how- 
ever, did  good  service  from  another  point  of  view,  when 
through  Eichter,  Dalton,  Proust,  and  Berzelius  the  fact 
that  bodies  combine  only  in  definite  proportions  of  weight, 
or  their  simple  multiples,  became  firmly  established.  The 
authors  of  this  discovery  were  driven  to  the  atomic  view 


1  See  also  Berthollet,  'Statique 
chimique,'  1803,  vol.  i.  :  "Les 
puissances  qui  produisent  les  phe'n- 
omenes  chimiques  sont  toutes  deVi- 
vees  de  1'attraction  mutuelle  des 
molecules  des  corps,  a  laquelle  on  a 
donne"  le  nom  d'affinite,  pour  la 
distinguer  de  1'attractiou  astrono- 
mique.  II  est  probable  que  1'une 
et  1'autre  ne  sont  qu'une  meme 
propriety"  (p.  1).  "II  y  a  des 
sciences  qui  peuvent  parvenir  a  un 
certain  degr6  de  perfection  sans  le 
secours  d'aucune  the'orie,  et  seule- 
tnent  par  le  moyen  d'un  ordre  ar- 
bitraire  qu'on  etablit  entre  les  obser- 
vations des  faits  naturels,  dont  elles 
s'occupent  principalement ;  mais 
il  n'en  est  pas  le  rneme  en  chimie, 
oil  les  observations  doivent  naitre 
presque  toujours  de  1'experience 
meme  et  ou  les  faits  resultent  de  la 
reunion  factice  des  circonstances  qui 
doivent  les  produire.  Pour  tenter 
les  experiences,  il  faut  avoir  un  but, 


etre  guide  par  une  hypothese.  .  .  . 
ainsi  les  suppositions  plus  ou  moms 
illusoires  et  meme  des  chimeres  qui 
sont  aujourd'hui  ridicules,  mais  qui 
ont  engage  aux  tentatives  les  plus 
laborieuses,  out  ete  necessaires,  au 
berceau  de  la  chimie.  Par  leur 
moyen  les  faits  se  sont  multiplies, 
un  grand  nombre  de  proprietes 
a  ete  constate,  et  plusieurs  arts 
se  sont  perfectionnes  "  (p.  4). 
"  Si  les  proprie"te"s  chimiques  des 
differentes  substances  sont  dues  a 
leur  affinite  et  a  leurs  dispositions 
particulieres,  celles  des  combin- 
aisons  qu'elles  forment  dependent 
de  la  saturation  respective,  des 
changements  de  constitution  qui 
sont  dus  a  1'action  reciproque,  du 
degre  de  la  force  qui  maintient  la 
combinaison  ;  ainsi  les  proprietes 
des  substances  simples  sont  non 
seulement  la  cause  des  combinaisons, 
mais  encore  celle  de  leurs  propres 
affections "  (vol.  ii.  p.  552). 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


417 


of  matter  as  the  most  convenient  method  of  expressing  the 
formulae  of  chemical  compounds.     Ever  since  that  time       23. 

A  conveni- 

the  atomic  view  has  served  as  a  kind  of  symbolism  by 
which  different  chemical  elements  could  be  characterised, 
their  compounds  described,  and  the  actual  weights  prac- 
tically calculated.  And  here  we  must  note  the  reserve 
with  which  some  of  the  greatest  representatives  of 
chemical  science  expressed  themselves  up  to  the  middle 
of  the  century  regarding  the  actual  physical  existence  of 
those  elementary  particles  with  which  they  operated  so 
freely  in  their  formulae,  and  which  they  even  represented 
by  balls  and  coloured  discs  in  their  demonstrations. 
Wollaston,  one  of  the  first  who  accepted  Dalton's1  views 


1  Dalton  does  not  seem  to  have 
been  troubled  by  any  philosophical 
doubts  or  by  the  anticipation  of 
the  mathematical  difficulties  which 
would  stand  in  the  way  of  a  con- 
sistent development  of  the  atomic 
view.  He  was  led  to  formulate  and 
employ  his  atomic  theory  by  ponder- 
ing over  the  most  convenient  man- 
ner in  which  certain  chemical  facts 
— the  facts  of  definite  and  multiple 
proportions — and  certain  physical 
discoveries — the  separate  existence 
of  aqueous  vapour  from  the  other 
constituents  of  the  air — could  be 
represented,  and  he  adopted  the 
view  suggested  by  Newton  in  his 
'  Queries,'  "that  matter  was  formed 
in  solid,  massy,  hard,  impenetrable, 
movable  particles "  (see  Sir  H. 
Roscoe,  '  John  Dalton,'  Century 
Series,  p.  128,  &c.)  Wollaston  and 
Davy  were  much  more  cautious  : 
the  former  foresaw  the  complicated 
and  far-reaching  mathematical  pro- 
blems which  were  involved  in  the 
atomic  view,  the  latter  thought 
the  generalisation  premature.  His 
labours  had  been  largely  in  the 
direction  of  showing  that  bodies 

VOL.  I. 


which  had  been  looked  upon  as 
elementary  were  compound,  and 
he  "  doubts  whether  we  have  yet 
obtained  elements"  (ibid.,  p.  155). 
Even  as  late  as  1826,  in  his  award 
to  Dalton  of  the  Royal  Medal,  he 
speaks  of  his  "  Development  of  the 
Chemical  Theory  of  Definite  Pro- 
portions, usually  called  the  Atomic 
Theory,"  he  emphasises  its  practical 
usefulness,  "making  the  statics  of 
chemistry  depend  upon  simple 
questions  in  subtraction  or  multi- 
plication, and  enabling  the  student 
to  deduce  an  immense  number  of 
facts  from  a  few  well  authenticated, 
accurate,  experimental  results."  He 
refers  to  Wollaston 's  table  of  equi- 
valents, which  "separates  the  prac- 
tical part  of  the  doctrine  from  the 
atomical  or  hypothetical  part."  It 
has,  in  fact,  been  maintained  that 
the  hesitancy  which  Wollaston  dis- 
played on  this  subject  deprived  him 
of  his  well-deserved  share  of  the 
glory  which  the  introduction  of  the 
atomic  view  of  matter  has  shed 
upon  Dalton  and  Berzelius.  (See 
Peacock,  '  Life  of  Dr  Young,'  p. 
469.) 

2D 


418 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


as  to  fixed  and  multiple  proportions,  expressed  himself 
with  great  reserve  as  to  the  value  of  the  atomic  hypothesis, 
and  when  drawing  up  a  table  of  atomic  weights,  he  pre- 
ferred to  call  them  equivalents — a  term  used  already  by 
Cavendish — as  implying  no  other  meaning  than  that  they 
fix  the  proportions  in  which  bodies  combine  into,  or  sep- 
arate out  of,  compounds.  Davy  was  hesitating  and  re- 
luctant to  admit  any  hypothesis  as  to  the  ultimate  con- 
stitution of  matter.  Liebig l  and  Faraday,2  at  a  somewhat 


1  "  In  endeavouring  to  develop 
the  theory  which  at  present  pre- 
vails respecting  the  cause  of  the 
unchangeableness  of  chemical  pro- 
portions, let  it  not  be  forgotten 
that  its  truth  or  falsehood  has 
nothing  whatever  to  do  with  the 
natural  law  itself.  The  latter  is 
the  expression  of  universal  experi- 
ence ;  it  remains  true,  invariably 
and  immutably,  however  our  no- 
tions respecting  its  cause  may  from 
time  to  time  vary  and  change." 
Thus  wrote  Liebig  ('  Familiar  Let- 
ters on  Chemistry,'  1844)  at  a  time 
when  great  confusion  existed  as  to 
the  real  atomic  or  smallest  com- 
bining weights  which  should  be 
assigned  to  the  chemical  elements  ; 
when  in  consequence  many  chemists 
preferred  to  discard  the  word 
"atomic  weight"  altogether,  and  to 
revert  to  the  term  equivalent  (see 
Kopp,  '  Entwickelung  der  Chemie,' 
p.  718,  &c.)  Dumas  in  1840  de- 
clared that  the  term  atomic  weight 
did  not  deserve  the  confidence  with 
which  chemists  made  use  of  it :  if 
he  could  he  would  banish  the  word 
atom  from  chemistry,  convinced  as 
he  was  that  science  should  not 
transgress  the  limit  of  that  which 
could  be  known  by  experience. 
Liebig,  in  1839,  about  the  time 
when  his  important  memoirs  on  the 
constitution  of  organic  bases  and 
acids  appeared  in  his  '  Annals,'  em- 


phasised likewise  the  fact  that 
equivalents  never  change  ;  but  he 
doubted  whether  chemists  would 
ever  agree  as  to  the  relative  atomic 
weights,  and  he  hoped  the  time  was 
not  far  distant  when  they  would 
all  return  again  to  equivalents 
(ibid.,  p.  438).  In  France  an  in- 
fluential school,  headed  by  the 
eminent  M.  Berthelot,  up  to  the 
present  day  limits  itself  to  the  use 
of  equivalents.  See  Berthelot,  '  La 
Synthese  chimique,'  7me  ed.,  p. 
164  n. 

2  The  objections  which  Faraday 
urged  against  the  notion  of  atom 
and  atomic  weight  seem  to  come 
from  a  different  quarter.  In  1834, 
when  explaining  his  researches  on 
electro  -  chemical  action,  he  says 
('Exper.  Res.,'  No.  869):  "If  we 
adopt  the  atomic  theory  or  phrase- 
ology, then  the  atoms  of  bodies 
which  are  equivalents  to  each  other 
in  their  ordinary  chemical  action 
have  equal  quantities  of  electricity 
naturally  associated  with  them. 
Bub  I  must  confess  I  am  jealous  of 
the  term  atom;  for  though  it  is 
very  easy  to  talk  of  atoms,  it  is 
very  difficult  to  form  a  clear  idea 
of  their  nature,  especially  when 
compound  bodies  are  under  consid- 
eration." Ten  years  later,  in  his 
'  Speculation  touching  Conduction 
and  the  Nature  of  Matter'  (see 
'Exper.  Res.,'  vol.  ii.  p.  285), 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


419 


later  date,  appeared  similarly  averse  to  admit  the  physical 
existence  of  atoms  in  the  older  sense,  and  warned  chemists 
against  the  introduction  of  unnecessary  and  unproven 
hypotheses.  Even  Gerhard t,  as  late  as  1856,  opposed 
the  idea  that  chemical  formula}  could  express  the  actual 
constitution  of  substances  :  they  were  merely  a  convenient 
symbolism,  a  kind  of  alphabet,  by  which  reactions  between 
different  elements  or  compounds  could  be  conveniently 
described,  and  the  proportional  weights  of  the  constituents 
or  the  products  could  be  ascertained.1  Accordingly,  it  was 
also  maintained  that  formula  could  be  written  in  very 
different  ways,  expressive  of  the  different  processes  and 
reactions  which  had  in  special  cases  to  be  considered.2 

Although,  therefore,  chemical  research  was  governed  all 
through  the  century  by  the  atomic  view  of  matter,  it  does 


he  says :  "  The  word  atom,  which 
can  never  be  used  without  involving 
much  that  is  purely  hypothetical, 
is  often  intended  to  be  used  to 
express  a  simple  fact.  .  .  .  There 
can  be  no  doubt  that  the  words 
•definite  proportions,  equivalents, 
primes,  &c.,  which  did  and  do  ex- 
press fully  all  the  facts  of  what  is 
usually  called  the  atomic  theory  in 
•chemistry,  were  dismissed  because 
they  were  not  expressive  enough, 
and  did  not  say  all  that  was  in  the 
mind  of  him  who  used  the  word 
atom  in  their  stead  ;  they  did  not 
express  the  hypothesis  as  well  as 
the  fact."  He  then  enlarges  on  the 
necessity  of  the  atomic  view,  and 
•expresses  his  preference  for  the  form 
which  Boscovich  had  given  to  it  over 
"  the  more  usual  notion,"  as  accord- 
ing to  the  latter  "  matter  consists 
of  atoms  and  intervening  space," 
whilst  with  the  former  "  matter  is 
•everywhere  present,  and  there  is  no 
intervening  space  unoccupied  by  it." 


(ibid.,  pp.  290,  291).  It  is  evidently 
the  objection  to  action  at  a  dis- 
tance, uncommunicated  action, 
which  is  implied  in  the  ordinary 
atomic  view  of  matter,  that  makes 
Faraday  jealous  of  the  term  atom. 
This  objection  was  quite  foreign 
to  the  chemists  abroad  who  in  the 
middle  of  the  century  elaborated 
the  atomic  view  of  matter  and  na- 
ture ;  it  belongs  to  a  different  direc- 
tion of  thought,  which  will  occupy 
us  in  a  later  chapter. 

1  In  his  'Trait^  de  Chimie  or- 
ganique,'  which  he  brought  out  as 
a  continuation  of  the  French  edi- 
tion of  Berzelius's  'Treatise  of  In- 
organic   Chemistry'   in    the   years 
1853   to   1856.     See  Kopp,   'Ent- 
wickelung  der    Chemie,'   pp.    747, 
796,  800,  809,  819,  834. 

2  Even    the    combining    weight 
or  equivalent  of  an  element,  that 
datum  upon  which — since  Richter 
and  Dalton — the  whole  system  of 
chemistry  has  been  built  up,  was 


420  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

not  appear  that  philosophers  considered  the  existence  and 
usefulness  of  chemical  formulae  as  a  proof  of  the  physical 
existence  of  atoms,  or  of  smallest  indivisible  particles  of 
matter,  in  the  older  sense  of  the  theory.  Hand  in  hand 
with  this  purely  formal  and  experimental  treatment  of 
«.  chemical  phenomena  went  the  almost  absolute  neglect 

Neglect  of 

witn  which  questions  referring  to  chemical  affinity  were 
treated.  The  word  was  little  more  than  a  name  for  an 
unknown  something. 

How  it  came  to  pass  that  substances  had  more  or  less 
affinity  for  each  other,  what  was  meant  by  a  chemical 
compound,  symbolically  expressed  by  writing  two  or  more 
letters,  near  or  above  each  other,  in  a  square  or  in  a  circle, 
united  by  parentheses  or  brackets,  did  not  seem  to  trouble 
chemical  philosophers  at  all.  To  compare  the  problem  of 
chemistry  with  that  of  astronomy,  the  former  for  a  great 
part  of  our  century  resembled  that  phase  of  astronomical 
knowledge  in  which  stellar  maps  and  catalogues,  plans  of 
orbits  and  orreries,  were  considered  sufficient,  giving  a  pic- 
ture of  a  certain  constellation  of  the  heavenly  bodies,  but 
no  idea  of  how  these  configurations  were  maintained  and 
altered.  In  fact,  chemistry  was  for  a  long  time  a  science 
purely  of  numbers,  to  which  was  attached  a  natural  his- 
tory of  the  substances  to  which  these  numbers  belonged. 
The  geometrical  arrangement  of  the  formulae  was  usually 
looked  upon  as  only  symbolical :  of  the  dynamical  changes 
which  take  place  in  time,  and  imply  the  knowledge  of 

considered    to   be    represented    by  Rendus/1844, voLxix. p.  1099, says: 

more    than    one    number    in    in-  "  Le  meme  corps  simple  se  presente 

stances  where  the  same  metal  had  tantot    avec    certaiues    proprietes, 

several  basic  or  acid  oxides,  as  in  tantot  avec  d'autres.  il  entre  dans 

the  case  of  nitrogen  and  phosphorus  les  corps  composes,  tantot  avec  un 

(ibid.,  p.  805).    Laurent  in '  Comptes  certain  poids,  tantot  avec  un  autre." 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


421 


forces  or  movements,  few  took  any  notice  whatever.  In 
spite  of  the  enormous  accumulation  of  well -arranged 
knowledge,  and  the  marvellous  practical  achievements  of 
chemistry,  the  foremost  historian  of  that  science  could, 
as  late  as  1873,  write  as  follows :  "  No  theory  has  as  yet  25. 
been  formed  in  chemistry  which,  starting  from  a  definite  chemical 

theory  in 

principle,  attempts  to  deduce  the  results  of  experience  as  1873- 
necessary  consequences.  The  doctrines  which  have  been 
termed  in  chemistry  theoretical  are  still  only  such  as  per- 
mit us  to  bring  connection  into  the  results  which  practical 
chemistry  has  gained  in  special  directions ;  or  to  form  a 
picture  how  we  might  think  of  them  as  mutually  related."1 


1  Kopp,  '  Entwickelung  der  Che- 
mie,'  1873,  p.  844.  A  generation 
earlier  Dumas  had  written  ('Comp- 
tes  Rendus,'  vol.  x.,  1840,  pp. 
171,  176,  178) :  "Dans  lea  vues  de 
1'electrochimie  la  nature  de  leurs 
particules  ele"mentaires  doit  deter- 
miner les  propriete's  fondamentales 
des  corps,  tandis  que  dans  la  thdorie 
des  substitutions,  c'est  de  la  situa- 
tion de  ces  particules,  que  les  pro- 
prietes  derivent  surtout.  .  .  .  La 
theorie  des  types  .  .  .  explique  ce 
que  la  loi  des  substitutions  se  con- 
tente  de  pre"ciser.  Elle  envisage 
les  corps  organiques  comme  e"tant 
forme's  des  particules,  qui  peuvent 
etre  de'place'es  et  remplacees,  sans 
que  le  corps  soit  detruit,  pour  ainsi 
dire.  .  .  .  Voila  done  en  presence 
deux  systeines :  1'un  qui  attribue 
le  role  principal  a  la  nature  des  ele- 
ments, 1'autre  qui  la  reserve  pour 
le  nombre  et  1'arrangement  des 
Equivalents.  Pousse  a  1'extreme 
chacun  d'eux  .  .  .  se  trouverait 
conduire  a  1'absurde."  In  1861 
Kekule,  in  his  '  Lehrbuch  der  or- 
gauischen  Chemie '  (vol.  i.  p.  95), 
declares  that,  "  besides  the  laws  of 
fixed  and  multiple  proportions  of 
weight  (and  in  gaseous  bodies  also 


of  volume),  chemistry  had  as  yet 
discovered  no  exact  laws,  .  .  .  and 
all  so-called  theoretical  conceptions 
were  merely  points  of  view  which 
possessed  probability  or  conveni- 
ence." And  Wurtz  ('La  ThEorie 
atomique,'  1863)  speaks  of  the 
atomic  hypothesis  in  terms  which 
might  lead  one  to  think  we  were  on 
the  eve  of  an  entirely  different  con- 
ception of  the  phenomena  of  nature : 
"Nous  retiendrons  1'hypothese  aussi 
longtemps  qu'elle  permettra  d'inter- 
prEter  fidelenfent  les  faits ;  de  les 
grouper,  de  les  relier  entre  eux  et 
d'en  prEvoir  de  nouveaux,  aussi 
longtemps,  en  un  mot,  qu'elle  se 
montrera  feconde  "  (p.  2).  "  Les 
considerations  sur  la  valeur  de  com- 
binaison  des  Elements  survivraient 
a  1'hypothese  des  atonies  si  celle-ci 
venait  a  etre  remplacEe  un  jour 
par  une  hypothese  plus  gEnErale. 
Mais  ce  jour  n'est  pas  arrivE ;  c'est 
vainetnent  qu'on  chercherait  a  dis- 
crediter  la  premiere  aussi  longtemps 
qu'elle  se  montrera  feconde.  Et  sa 
fecondite,  sa  puissance  Eclatent  dans 
les  progres  incessants  de  la  science. 
C'est  elle  qui  vivifie  les  dEcouvertes 
les  plus  recentes,  comme  elle  a  Etc 
depuis  Dalton  son  immortel  auteur, 


422  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

This  statement  implies  that  even  as  late  as  the  end  of  the 
third  quarter  of  the  century,  foremost  thinkers  hesitated  to 
attach  a  more  than  provisional  importance  to  chemical  sym- 
bolism and  the  various  elaborations  of  the  atomic  theory, 
as  chemical  text-books  then  exhibited  them.  Similar 
merely  provisional  theories  have  existed  in  other  branches 
of  science.  The  theory  of  the  two  fluids  in  electricity 
did  good  service  for  a  long  time  in  enabling  philosophers 
to  define  their  ideas,  to  describe,  calculate,  and  predict 
phenomena.  In  optics,  the  so-called  corpuscular  theory 
of  light  is  still  used  with  advantage  as  a  convenient 
means  of  summarising  the  laws  of  reflexion  and  re- 
fraction ;  similarly,  in  treatises  on  the  conduction  of  heat, 
the  old  caloric  theory  still  holds  a  place  alongside  of  the 
26.  more  modern  dynamical  views.  It  niav  be  questioned 

The  periodic 

few-  whether  the  celebrated  periodic  law  of  Xewlands,  Lothar 

Meyer,  and  Mendeleeff,  which  has  brought  some  order 
into  the  atomic  and  other  numbers  referring  to  the  dif- 
ferent elements,  and  has  even  made  it  possible  to  predict 
the  existence  of  unknown  elements  with  definite  pro- 
perties, stands  really  in  a  firmer  position  than  the  once 
well-known  but  now  forgotten  law  of  Bode,1  according  to 

Finstrument  le   plus   parfait  pour  *  According  to  the  relation,  first 

lea  conceptions  elevens  de  la  the'orie  observed    by    Christian  Wolff  and 

et  le   guide  le   plus   sur   pour  les  Daniel  Titius,  that  the  distances  of 

recherchesexpe'rimentale8"(p.241).  \   the  planets  from  the  sun  obey  ap- 

And  quite  mournfully  does  Kopp  re-  '   proximately  the  formula   Q'4  +  0'3 

port  at  the  close  of  his  historical  sur-  i    x  2",  where  n  for  Venus,  Earth, 

vey  of  the  development  of  chemistry  Mars,  &c.,  assumes  the  values  0,  1,2, 

('Entwickelung,'&c.,p.829)how  that  &c.,    the    planet  corresponding   to 

science  about  1860  again  "turned  «  =  3  was  missing.     When,  on  the 

into  the  course  which  it  had  tried  so  \   discovery  of  Uranus  in  1781 ,  it  was 

often,  and  had  so  often  abandoned  found   that   this   planet's  distance 

as  hopeless,  endeavouring  to  gain  also  agrees  approximately  with  the 

a  knowledge   how  the  elementary  formula,  Bode  and  von  Zach  drew 

atoms  are  arranged  in  the  smallest  attention  to  this  fact,  and  suggested 

particles  of  their  compounds."  a  systematic  search  for  the  missing 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


423 


which  the  gap  in  the  series  which  gives  the  distances 
of  the  planets  from  the  sun  indicated  the  existence  of  a 


planet,  "a  chercher  une  aiguille  dans 
une   botte   de   foin."      About   the 
same    time    that    this    search   was 
contemplated  Piazzi  found  the  first 
of  the  small  planets,  which — like 
the  other  subsequently  discovered 
asteroids — corresponds  very  nearly 
with  the  expected  position  in  the 
system.      The    periodic   system   of 
the   elements,  according  to  which 
the     physical    and    chemical    pro- 
perties  of   all   the   elements  show 
a   periodic    dependence    upon    the 
atomic  weights,  was   first   system- 
atically   stated    by    Newlands    (in 
1864)   and    by   Lothar   Meyer   and 
MendeleeiF  on  the  Continent.     The 
latest  edition  of  Meyer's  treatise  on 
"Modern  Theories  of  Chemistry,"  of 
which  only  the  first  part,  with  the 
title  '  Die  Atome  und  ihre  Eigen- 
schaften  '  has  been  published  (post- 
humously by  the  author's  brother, 
Breslau,  1896),  gives  a  good  idea  of 
how  from   small  beginnings   these 
statistics  of  the  atomic  theory  of 
matter    have   grown    into   a  great 
accumulation    of   interesting  facts, 
upon  which  a  system  of  inorganic 
chemistry  can  now  be  based  which 
compares  with   the  system  of  or- 
ganic chemistry  founded  upon  the 
types   of   Gerhardt   in    their  orig- 
inal   or    in    some    modified    form, 
and  upon  the  "homologous"  series 
of    hydrocarbon    compounds.       As 
the  typical  arrangement  of  organic 
compounds,    or    rather    of    carbon 
compounds  (for  many  real  organic 
compounds   are   not   easily   classed 
by  these  methods),  led  to  the  sug- 
gestion of  the   existence  of  many 
compounds  which  were  not  known 
at  the  time,  and  have  since  been 
prepared,  so  the  periodic  arrange- 
ment enabled  Mendeleeff  to  predict 
the  properties  of  missing  numbers 
of    the    periodic    series.      And   al- 
though  this   mapping   out  of   the 


elements  according  to  their  atomic 
weights  does  not  indicate  how  and 
where  the  missing  numbers  are  to 
be  found,  as  is  the  case  with  the 
law  of  Titius  and  Bode,  and  still 
more  so  with  the  homologous  series 
of    carbon    compounds,    still   it  is 
interesting  to  be  able  to  state  that 
in   several    instances  —  notably   on 
the  discovery  of  the  new  elements, 
gallium  (by  Lecoq  de  Boisbaudran 
in  1878),  scandium  (by  Nilsou   in 
1880),  and  germanium  (by  Winkler 
in   1886)  —  the  properties  of  these 
substances    confirmed    to    a    very 
great    extent    the    predictions    of 
Mendele"ett'.      And    when    in    1894 
Lord  Rayleigh  and  Professor  Ram- 
say announced  their  discovery  of  a 
new   element  in   atmospheric    air, 
which,    from     its     inertness,     was 
called    argon,    interesting    sugges- 
tions   as    to    its    properties    were 
drawn  from  speculations  regarding 
its  probable  position  in  the  periodic 
curve  (see  Lothar  Meyer,  loc.  cit., 
p.    165).      It    is    true    that    these 
numerical    regularities,    which    for 
some  minds  possess  a  great  fascina- 
tion, are,  so  far,  purely  statistical. 
It   is   possible  to  arrive  by  inter- 
polation or  extrapolation  at  valu- 
able   suggestions    in    statistics,    in 
meteorology,  and  in  mining  opera- 
tions ;   but   so   long  as  the  actual 
cause  or  intrinsic  connection  is  not 
known,  which  explains  the  neces- 
sity of  these  regularities,  they  are 
apt  to  be  misleading,  and  have  to 
be  used  with  great  caution.     Still, 
the  fact  alone  that  they  bring  some 
order   into  a   bewildering  mass   of 
figures   and   data  makes   them   al- 
most   indispensable.       For    similar 
reasons    many    chemists     adopted 
Gerhardt's   types  and  homologous 
series  as  affording  a  ready  method 
of  classification,  though  not  a  ra- 
tional explanation  of  phenomena. 


424 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


27. 


planet  between  Mars  and  Jupiter,  anticipating  the  dis- 
covery of  the  Asteroids,  which  have  accordingly  been 
regarded  as  the  fragments  of  the  missing  planet. 

It  thus  appears  that  purely  "  chemical  reasoning,"  as  it 
has  been  called,  has  proved  insufficient  to  establish  the 

chemical 

and  physical  atomic  view  of   nature  on  the  same  firm  basis  as  has 

reasoning. 

supported  the  mechanical  or  astronomical  view  ever  since 
the  age  of  Galileo  and  Xewton.1  In  the  second  half  of 
the  century,  the  atomic  view  of  matter  has  however 
been  put  forward  from  a  different  side,  and  independent 
researches  have,  in  combination  with  the  older  chemical 
theories,  introduced  so  much  definiteness  into  this  line 
of  thought  that  "  the  Newtonian  theory  of  gravitation  is 


1  "Many  diagrams  and  models 
of  compound  molecules  have  been 
constructed.  These  are  the  re- 
cords of  the  efforts  of  chemists  to 
imagine  configurations  of  material 
systems  by  the  geometrical  rela- 
tions of  which  chemical  phenomena 
may  be  illustrated  or  explained. 
No  chemist,  however,  professes  to 
see  in  these  diagrams  anything 
more  than  symbolic  representations 
of  the  various  degrees  of  closeness 
with  which  the  different  com- 
ponents of  the  molecule  are  bound 
together.  In  astronomy,  on  the 
other  hand,  the  configurations  and 
motions  of  the  heavenly  bodies  are 
on  such  a  scale  that  we  can  ascer- 
tain them  by  direct  observation ; 
.  .  .  the  doctrine  of  universal  gravi- 
tation not  only  explains  the  ob- 
served motions  of  our  system,  but 
enables  us  to  calculate  the  motions 
of  the  system  in  which  the  astro- 
nomical elements  may  have  any 
values  whatever"  (Clerk  Maxwell, 
"On  the  Dynamical  Evidence 
of  the  Molecular  Constitution  of 
Bodies,"  June  1875,  'Scientific 
Papers,'  vol.  iL  p.  418).  "The 


chemists  ascertain  by  experiment 
the  ratios  of  the  masses  of  the 
different  substances  in  a  compound. 
From  these  they  deduce  the  chemi- 
cal equivalents  of  the  different  sub- 
stances, that  of  a  particular  sub- 
stance being  taken  as  unity.  The 
only  evidence  made  use  of  is  that 
furnished  by  chemical  combination. 
It  is  also  assumed,  in  order  to  ac- 
count for  the  facts  of  combination, 
that  the  reason  why  substances 
combine  in  definite  ratios  is.  that 
the  molecules  of  the  substances 
are  in  the  ratio  of  their  chemical 
equivalents,  and  that  what  we  call 
combination  is  an  action  which 
takes  place  by  a  union  of  a  mole- 
cule of  one  substance  to  a  molecule 
of  the  other.  This  kind  of  reason- 
ing, when  presented  in  a  proper 
form,  and  sustained  by  proper  evi- 
dence, has  a  high  degree  of  cogency. 
But  it  is  purely  chemical  reasoning  ; 
it  is  not  dynamical  reasoning.  It 
is  founded  on  chemical  experience, 
not  on  the  laws  of  motion "  (Id. 
article  "  Atom,"  '  Ency.  Brit.,'  1675 ; 
ibid.,  vol.  ii.  p.  456). 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


425 


not  surer  to  us  now  than  is  the  atomic  or  molecular 
theory  in  chemistry  and  physics  —  so  far,  at  all  events,  as 
its  assertion  of  heterogeneousness  in  the  minute  structure 
of  matter,  apparently  homogeneous  to  our  senses,  and  to 
our  most  delicate  direct  instrumental  tests."  1 

This  side  of  the  atomic  view  of  matter  has  been  de- 
veloped  by  the  study  of  the  properties  of  bodies  in  the 
gaseous  state,  and,  in  its  modern  form,  goes  back  to  the 
experiments  of  Gay-Lussac,  which  were  almost  simul- 
taneous with  those  of  Dalton.2  It  is  interesting  to  note 
how  little  the  latter  recognised  the  importance  of  these 
researches,  when  he  rejected  the  so-called  law  of  volumes, 
according  to  which  gases,  under  the  same  pressure,  and 
at  equal  temperatures,  enter  into,  or  separate  out  of, 
chemical  combination  in  definite  and  very  simple  pro- 
portions of  their  volume.  As,  according  to  the  law  of 
definite  proportions,  bodies  (including  gases)  combine  only 


1  Lord  Kelvin  on  ' '  Capillary  At- 
traction," 1886.     See  '  Popular  Lec- 
tures and  Addresses,'  vol.  i.  p.  4. 

2  The   first  results   referring   to 
the  combining  volumes  of  oxygen 
and  hydrogen  gas  in  forming  water 
were    given    by    Gay  -  Lussac    and 
Humboldt  in  a  joint  memoir.    Their 
experiments    were    carried    on    in 
1805.    Gay-Lussac  continued  the  ex- 
periments alone,  extended  them  to 
gaseous  compounds,  and  published 
his  results  in  1809  in  the  second 
volume  of  the  '  Memoires  d'Arcueil.' 
This  was  one  year  after  the  publi- 
cation  of   Dalton's    '  New   System 
of   Chemical   Philosophy,'  and  two 
years  after  Thomas  Thomson  had 
published  a  sketch  of  the  atomic 
theory  in  his  text-book  on  Chem- 
istry.    The  law  of  equal  expansion 
of  all  gases  with  temperature  was 
published  by  Dalton  in  1801  ;  the 


law  of  pressures — that  the  volume 
of  a  gas,  at  the  same  temperature, 
is  inversely  as  the  pressure — was 
published  by  Boyle  in  1662.  It 
goes  on  the  Continent  under  the 
name  of  Mariotte,  who  first  made 
it  generally  known  about  twelve 
years  later  (see  on  this  the  fourth 
appendix  to  the  2ud  edition  of 
Tait's  '  Properties  of  Matter,'  1890). 
The  law  of  temperatures  was  pub- 
lished in  1802  by  Gay-Lussac  in 
the  '  Annales  de  Chimie  et  de  Phys- 
ique" (vol.  xliii.  p.  137),  where  he 
remarks  that  Charles,  Professor  of 
Physics  at  the  "  Conservatoire,"  had 
fifteen  years  earlier  noted  the  prop- 
erty indicated  by  this  law.  Both 
these  so-called  laws  of  gases  are 
only  accurate  within  certain  [not 
very  wide  limits  of  temperature  and 
pressure. 


28. 

The  kinetic 


426  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

according  to  definite  proportions  of  their  weight,  it  follows 
that  in  the  gaseous  state  these  combining  weights  of  bodies 
have  either  equal  volumes  or  such  as  stand  in  very  simple 
proportions.  Now  the  amount  of  matter  (measured  by 
weight)  in  the  same  volume  is  called  the  density  of  a  gas. 
It  therefore  follows,  by  putting  Dalton's  and  Gay-Lussac's 
discoveries  together,  that  the  combining  weights  of  gases 
are  either  directly  proportional  to  their  densities  or  to  a 
simple  multiple  thereof.  Some  years  after  this  discovery 
in  1809,  Gay-Lussac  extended  his  statement  so  as  not 
only  to  embrace  elementary  gases,  such  as  hydrogen, 
oxygen,  and  nitrogen,  but  also  compounds,  such  as  am- 
monia, carbonic  acid,  hydrochloric  acid,  and  showed  how, 
if  they  enter  into  chemical  combination,  they  likewise  do 
so  in  the  simple  proportions  of  one  volume  of  one,  to  one 
or  two  volumes  of  the  other. 

Whilst  chemists  such  as  Gay-Lussae,  Berzelius,  and 
others1  recognised  in  the  facts  discovered  by  the  first  a 

1  Dalton  was  the  only  person  who  weight,    and    that  in   consequence 

doubted    the   correctness  of   Gay-  great  uncertainty  reigned  for  a  long 

Lussac's     figures,     although     both  time  in   these  matters.      This  in- 

Thomson  and  Berzelius  pointed  out  duced  L.  Gmelin  to  disregard  the 

to  him  the  great  support  they  volumetric  relations  in  his  system 
afforded  to  the  atomic  theory,  j  of  equivalents,  to  the  great  detri- 

Berzelius  also  saw  the   usefulness  ment  of  those  who  in  the  middle  of 

of  the  law  of  volumes  in  fixing  the  the  century  were  brought  up  with 
smallest  combining  or  atomic  num-  |  very  vague  and  unsatisfactory  ex- 

bers  in  cases  where  the  reference  to  planations  on  this  subject — differ  - 

weight  alone  left  the  matter  unde-  ent  numbers  being  used  in  books 

tided.     Thus  he  correctly  inferred  on  organic  and  inorganic  chemistry, 

that  the  formula  of  water  should  A  great  confusion  existed  at  that 

be  H20,  as  we  write  it  to-day,  be-  time,  Gerhardt  showing  good  rea- 

cause    two    volumes    of    hydrogen  sons,  based  upon  his  observations  of 

combined  with  one  of  oxygen.     But  the  substitution  of  hydrogen  in  or- 

it  was   unfortunate   that,  through  game  compounds  and  the  system  of 

his  want  of  appreciation  of  Avo-  classification  which  he  introduced, 

gadro's  further  expositions,  he  was  why    several    of    Gmelin's    figures 

unable  to  reconcile  more  completely  should  be  doubled  ;  but  the  matter 

the  appeal  to  volume  with  that  to  was  not  cleared  up  till  Cannizzaro 


THE   ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE.  427 

method  for  determining  the  combining  weights  of  elements 
or  their  simple  multiples,  they  did  not  draw  the  natural 
consequences  as  to  the  physical  constitution  of  bodies  in 
the  gaseous  state  which  followed  from  these  and  other 
facts  which  had  been  known  before.  It  had  been  known 
since  the  time  of  Boyle  and  Mariotte  that  equal  volumes  of 
different  gases  under  equal  pressure  change  their  volumes 
equally  if  the  pressure  is  varied  equally,  and  it  was  also 
known  through  Gay-Lussac  himself  that  equal  volumes  of 
different  gases  under  equal  pressure  change  their  volumes 
equally  with  equal  rise  of  temperature.  The  like  be-  29. 

Avogadro's 

haviour  of  equal  volumes  of  different  gases  towards  pres-  hypothesis, 
sure,  temperature,  and  chemical  combination  suggested 
to  Avogadro,  and  almost  simultaneously  to  Ampere,  the 
very  simple  assumption  that  this  is  owing  to  the  fact  that 
equal  volumes  of  different  gases  contain  an  equal  num- 
ber of  smallest  independent  particles  of  matter.  This  is 
Avogadro's  celebrated  hypothesis.  It  was  the  first  step  in 
the  direct  physical  verification  of  the  atomic  view  of  mat- 
ter, and  if  maintained  by  further  experience,  it  was  des- 
tined to  be  one  of  the  most  important  proofs  of  this  view. 
But  this  assumption  or  hypothesis  had  to  be  reconciled 
with  facts.  It  was,  for  instance,  observed  that  a  given 
quantity  of  hydrochloric  acid  gas  occupied  the  same 


showed  the  real  meaning  and  im-  ally  the  graphic  description  by  L. 

portance  of  Avogadro's  hypothesis.  Meyer  himself  of  the  meeting  held 

A  good  exposition  of  the  difference  in    September    1860   at   Carlsruhe 

of  opinions  which  were  held  at  that  for  the  purpose  of  ventilating  these 

time  will  be  found  in  A.  Wurtz,  important  theoretical  questions  (L. 

'  La  Theorie  atomique,'  p.  55,  &c.  Meyer's  translation  of  Cannizzaro's 

See  also  Prof.   Bedson's  '  Memorial  '  Sunto    di    un     corso    di    filosofia 

Lecture'  on  Lothar  Meyer  (1896),  chitnica,'    in    Ostwald's    'Classiker 
in    the  'Journal   of   the   Chemical   ;   der  exacten  Wissenschaften,'   No. 

Society,'  p.   519,   &c.,   and  especi-  30,  Appendix,  p.  58). 


428 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


volume  as  did  each  of  the  equivalent  quantities,  hydrogen 
and  chlorine,  out  of  which  it  was  compounded,  and  it 
appeared  that  accordingly  double  the  number  of  atoms 
were  condensed  into  the  same  volume.  To  explain  this, 
and  yet  maintain  his  original  hypothesis,  Avogadro  was 
forced  into  the  conception  of  compound  atoms  or  particles 
— i.e.,  into  the  assumption  that  the  smallest  independent 
particles  need  not  be  the  elementary  atoms  of  hydrogen 
and  chlorine  themselves,  but  might  be  made  up  of  two 
or  more  of  such  atoms,  chemically  connected  in  such 
a  way  that  the  expansion  of  the  gas  under  increasing 
temperature  or  decreasing  pressure  did  not  affect  this 
complex  of  elementary  particles.1  Such  a  compound 


1  Avogadro  published  his  memoir 
in  the  'Journal  de  Physique'  in 
1811,  and  Ampere  expounded  simi- 
lar views  three  years  later  in  the 
form  of  a  letter  to  Berthollet  in  the 
'  Annales  de  Chimie. '  Neither  the 
celebrity  of  Ampere  nor  the  ex- 
haustive explanations  of  Avogadro, 
who  was  then  an  unknown  author, 
prevented  this  hypothesis,  which 
is  now  looked  upon  as  a  corner- 
stone of  the  atomic  view,  from 
falling  into  oblivion.  Whewell 
does  not  mention  it.  Even  Kopp, 
whose  labours  for  many  years 
covered  a  field  little  cultivated  by 
most  other  chemists,  that  of  physi- 
cal chemistry,  makes  no  mention 
of  Avogadro's  and  Ampere's  hypo- 
thesis in  his  great  work  on  the 
History  of  Chemistry,  published 
between  the  years  1843  and  1847. 
In  his  later  work  ('Die  Entwickelung 
der  Chemie,'  1873)  he  enters  ela- 
borately into  the  causes  which  made 
chemical  philosophers  overlook  so 
valuable  a  suggestion  (p.  353,  ic,) 
Like  WhewelFs  History,  Poggen- 
dorfs  Dictionary  (1863)  was  sil- 
ent about  Avogadro.  The  distinc- 


tion between  molecules  and  atoms 
seemed  to  complicate  matters  ;  be- 
sides, the  new  hypothesis  was  not 
launched  in  conjunction  with  any 
new  experimental  discoveries,  as 
had  been  the  case  with  Dalton's, 
Davy's,  and  Gay-Lussac;s  theories. 
The  first  who  again  drew  attention 
to  the  subject  was  Dumas,  who  in 
1826  began  his  investigations  re- 
garding the  specific  weight  of 
vapours — i.e.,  of  bodies  in  a  gaseous 
state.  He  there  drew  attention  to 
the  necessity  of  distinguishing  be- 
tween chemical  and  physical  par- 
ticles, but  he  does  not  yet  con- 
sistently use  the  terms  atom  and 
molecule  to  denote  the  former  and 
the  latter.  In  the  meantime,  how- 
ever, a  very  important  step  had 
been  taken  in  the  development  of 
the  atomic  view.  In  1819  Dulong  and 
Petit  published  their  experimental 
researches  concerning  the  specific 
heat  of  a  large  number  of  element- 
ary bodies — i.e..  the  measured  quan- 
tities of  heat  (compared  with  a 
standard  substance)  which  were 
required  to  raise  a  number  of 
metals  by  one  degree  in  tempera- 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


429 


atom  or  complex  was  termed  a  molecule,  and  it  was 
assumed  that  molecules,  or  smallest  individual  particles 
of  chemical  substances,  might  be  made  up  of  one  or  more 
atoms  of  the  same  or  of  different  substances.  Avogadro 
was  able  in  this  way  to  explain  how  a  certain  number  of 
molecules  of  hydrogen — each  made  up  of  two  atoms — 
combine  with  an  equal  number  of  molecules  of  chlorine ; 
these  being  likewise  composed  of  two  atoms  of  chlorine, 
in  order  to  form  an  equal  number  of  molecules  of  hydro- 
chloric acid,  each  of  these  consisting  of  two  atoms — viz., 
one  of  chlorine  and  one  of  hydrogen.  This  view,  which  30. 
Ampere  likewise  adopted,  did  not  recommend  itself  to  same?0 
chemists  for  many  years ;  not  indeed  till,  about  the  year 
1840,  several  eminent  chemists — notably  Laurent — were 
independently  led  to  consider  chemical  compounds  as 
formed  by  what  is  termed  substitution  instead  of  simple 
combination.1  For,  according  to  Avogadro's  view,  the  for- 


ture.  They  then  found  that  these 
quantities  stood  very  nearly  in  in- 
verse proportions  to  the  atomic  or 
combining  numbers.  They  at  the 
same  time  pointed  out  the  un- 
certainty which  —  in  consequence 
of  the  law  of  fixed  multiple  pro- 
portions —  existed  regarding  the 
smallest  figure  which  was  to  deter- 
mine the  combining  weights  ;  they 
chose  those  numbers  which  brought 
out  clearly  the  physical  regularity 
and  coincidence  which  they  had  dis- 
covered ;  and  they  expressed  their 
result  in  the  rule  that  the  atoms  of 
all  elementary  bodies  have  the  same 
capacity  for  heat.  Whereas  Ber- 
zelius  ignored  the  theoretical  dis- 
cussions of  Avogadro  and  Ampere, 
he  hailed  the  experimental  data 
of  Dulong  and  Petit  as  most  useful 
in  helping  to  fix  correctly  the  real 
equivalent  numbers,  a  task  to  which, 


as  the  fundamental  requisite  of  all 
chemistry,  he  devoted  so  much  time 
and  labour.  It  must,  however,  be 
noted  that  the  law  of  Dulong  and 
Petit,  now  universally  accepted  as 
a  fundamental  fact  in  the  atomic 
theory,  is,  as  little  as  the  laws  of 
Boyle,  Charles,  and  Gay  -  Lussac, 
rigidly  correct :  it  obtains  within 
certain  limits.  The  experiments 
of  Dulong  and  Petit  were  extended 
to  compounds  by  F.  Neumann  in 
1831.  The  connection  of  the  specific 
heat  or  thermal  capacity  of  com- 
pounds and  that  of  their  con- 
stituents was  fully  investigated  by 
Regnault.  A  statement  of  the  diffi- 
culties and  anomalies  which  still 
exist  will  be  found  in  L.  Meyer's 
'  Die  Atome  und  ihre  Eigenschaften' 
(p.  73,  &c.)  _ 

1  A  very  important  influence  in 
contributing  to  the  gradual  recog- 


430 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


mation  of  the  molecule  of  hydrochloric  acid  depended  upon 
an  exchange  of  places  of  the  atomic  constituents  in  the 
molecules  of  the  elementary  substances,  an  atom  of  chlor- 
ine being  substituted  for  an  atom  of  hydrogen  in  the 
hydrogen  molecule,  and  vice  versd  in  the  chlorine  molecule. 
About  the  middle  of  this  century  the  conviction  was  thus 
firmly  established  in  the  minds  of  chemical  philosophers 
that  the  simple  symbolism  by  which  Daltoii  and  Berzelius 
expressed  chemical  combinations  and  processes  was  in- 
sufficient for  the  purpose  of  systematically  arranging  the 


nition  of  the  difference  between 
atom  and  molecule  belongs  also  to 
Gerhardt,  who  emphasised  a  fact 
known  already  to  Berzelius — viz., 
that  hydrogen  according  to  his 
notation  appeared  to  combine  with 
other  bodies  always  in  paired  atoms. 
This  fact  remained  unnoticed  if  the 
atomic  number'  of  hydrogen  was 
put  at  1,  oxygen  at  8,  as  was  done  by 
English  chemists  and  reintroduced 
by  Gmelin.  Berzelius  did  not  attach 
a  fundamental  importance  to  this 
fact.  Blomstrand  (' Die  Chemie  der 
Jetztzeit,'  1869,  p.  30)  has  shown 
that  this  originated  in  his  clinging 
to  Lavoisier's  oxygen  theory.  Oxy- 
gen was  made  the  centre  and  meas- 
ure of  everything  in  chemistry,  also 
of  the  equivalence  of  substances : 
Berzelius  thus  started  from  a 
unit  which  was  too  large,  and  with 
which  the  smaller  value  of  hydrogen 
could  not  be  measured.  Gerhardt 
fully  recognised  the  importance 
of  this  fact ;  showed  in  many 
examples  that  the  combining  or 
atomic  weight  of  hydrogen  had 
been  fixed  too  high ;  and  proposed 
to  halve  most  of  the  organic  for- 
mula. In  this  way  he  proposed 
to  bring  harmony  into  the  theory 
of  combining  volumes  and  the 
atomic  theory.  He  partially  suc- 
ceeded in  doing  so,  although  in  the 


case  of  inorganic  elements  he  went 
too  far.  This  important  step, 
which  has  been  extolled  by  some, 
and  depreciated  by  other  historians 
of  chemistry,  is  lucidly  expounded 
by  Rau  in  his  'Theorien  der  mo- 
dernen  Chemie '  (vol.  ii.  p.  107,  &c.) 
"\Vurtz  ('Theorie  atomique,' p.  64) 
considers  Gerhardt's  influence  as  a 
reform,  and  alludes  to  it  as  bringing 
again  into  view  the  hypothesis  of 
Avogadro  :  "Voilale  theme  d'Avo- 
gadro  et  d'Ampere,  qui  revient  a 
1'horizon,  comme  uue  etoile  diri- 
geante,  apres  uue  longue  eclipse. 
Et  pourtant  on  ne  peut  pas  dire 
qu'elle  ait  etc  pour  Gerhardt,  a 
cette  epoque  du  rnoins,  un  guide 
exclusif.  Les  considerations  mai- 
tresses  qu'il  a  invoquees  sont  plutot 
d'ordre  purement  chimique.  Elles 
e"taient  justes,  et  il  s'est  trouve 
qu'elles  concordaient  avec  une  idee 
egalement  juste,  et  qui  e"tait  tombe'e 
dans  1'oubli.  La  distinction  entre 
deux  especes  de  petites  particules, 
molecules  et  atomes,  qu'Avogadro 
et  Ampere  avaient  introduite  in- 
utilement  dans  la  science,  que  M. 
Dumas  avait  essaye"  de  faire  revivre 
dans  sa  Philosophie  chimique,  cette 
distinction  e"tait  peut  -  etre  faite 
dans  1'esprit  de  Gerhardt,  mais  elle 
n'apparaissait  pas  encore  dans  son 
langage." 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


431 


growing  volume  of  chemical  knowledge  ;  that  the  concep-        si. 
tion  of  the  atom  must  be  extended  and  more  closely  de-  mentor  the 

atomic  view. 

fined ;  that  the  proportions  of  weight  were  inadequate  for 
the  purpose  of  distinguishing  and  identifying  the  many 
organic  compounds ;  and  especially  that  the  relations  of 
volume  and  the  arrangements  of  particles  of  matter  in  space 
must  be  taken  notice  of,  if  the  atomic  view  of  matter  was 
to  be  made  further  serviceable  for  scientific  purposes.  That 
purely  geometrical  relations,  such  as  can  be  grasped  only 
by  our  space  conceptions,  are  of  importance  in  the  chem- 
ical composition  of  substances,  was  very  evident,  for 
instance,  in  some  of  the  optical  properties  of  crystallised 
organic  substances.  The  discoveries  of  Pasteur,  published  32. 
in  1850,  mark  in  this  respect  an  epoch  in  science.1  He  discovery  of 

*          .         z  "chirality." 

showed  that  there  exist  chemical  substances  which  are 
different,  but  only  as  a  right-hand  glove  differs  from  a 
left-hand  one,  a  right-handed  screw  from  a  left-handed, 


1  A  special  line  of  "physical "  or 
"mechanical"  reasoning  which  bears 
upon  the  atomic  view  of  matter  be- 
gan with  Biot's  discovery  in  1815 
that  certain  fluids — notably  organic 
— have  the  property  of  rotating  the 
plane  of  polarisation  of  light  which 
passes  through  them.  Later  on  he 
extended  this  observation  to  the 
vapours  formed  by  such  fluids. 
Faraday  found  in  1846  that  sub- 
stances which  are  optically  "  in- 
active "  become  active  in  the 
manner  described  under  the  influ- 
ence of  powerful  electro-magnets. 
An  explanation  of  the  phenomenon 
by  Fresnel,  which  was  based  upon 
crystalline  structure,  would  —  for 
liquids  and  vapours  —  have  to  be 
applied  to  the  structure  of  the  mole- 
cule itself.  Pasteur  found  in  1850 
that  there  exist  two  modifications 


of  tartaric  acid,  which  differ  in  this 
only,  that  one  of  them  turns  the 
plane  of  polarisation  to  the  right, 
the  other  to  the  left,  and  that  a 
mixture  of  both  in  the  proper  pro- 
portions is  inactive.  As  far  back 
as  1860,  in  his  '  Leyons  de  Chimie,' 
he  put  the  question,  "whether 
the  atoms  in  tartaric  acid  are  ar- 
ranged like  the  turns  of  a  right- 
handed  screw,  or  situated  in  the 
corners  of  an  irregular  tetrahedron, 
or  have  they  any  other  asymmetrical 
grouping?  .  .  .  There  can  be  no  doubt 
that  the  atoms  have  an  unsym- 
metrical  arrangement  after  the  fash- 
ion of  mirrored  images  which  cannot 
be  made  to  fall  into  each  other  " 
(quoted  by  Van't  Hoff,  '  Die  Lager- 
ung  der  Atome  im  Raume,'  Ger- 
man translation,  2nd  ed.,  p.  9). 


432  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

the  image  in  a  mirror  from  the  original.  Was  it  possible 
any  longer  to  suppress  the  conviction  that  the  smallest 
particles  of  matter,  in  forming  chemical  compounds,  do 
so  not  only  in  definite  proportions  of  weight,  but  also  in 
definite  geometrical  distances  and  positions  ? 

About  the  middle  of  the  century  the  atomic  view  of 
matter  had  thus  received  considerable  modifications.  Or- 
iginally suggested  only  to  explain,  describe,  or  symbolise 
the  fact  that  different  substances  combine  in  fixed,  and 
especially  in  fixed  multiple  proportions,  it  had  to  be 
modified  by  a  recognition  of  the  fact  that  in  gases  at  least 
a  distinction  exists  between  particles  which  are  closely 
knit  together — as  it  were,  geometrically  inseparable — and 
such  as  can  move  away  from  each  other.  The  latter 
explain  the  increase  of  volume  under  increasing  tempera- 
ture or  decreasing  pressure.  Geometrical  distance  came 
in  as  the  means  of  distinguishing  the  molecule  from  the 
atom.  And  lastly,  about  1850,  the  phenomena  of  right- 
and  left-handedness,1  discovered  by  Pasteur,  suggested  the 
33.  idea  of  geometrical  position  as  well  as  of  distance.  The 
molecule,  atom  had  become  a  molecule,  with  a  definite  geometrical 
arrangement. 

It  took,  however,  a  full  generation  before,  in  the  second 
half  of  the  century,  these  different  suggestions  for  a  modi- 
fication of  the  atomic  view  became  clear,  before  philo- 
sophers took  seriously  the  opinion  that  molecules  and 
atoms  existed  in  reality,  and  were  not  merely  a  convenient 
symbolism,  as  many  great  chemists  during  the  first  half 
of  the  century  were  inclined  to  think.  This  change  in 
the  habit  of  chemical  thought  has  no  doubt  been"  greatly 

1  Called  by  Lord  Kelvin  "chirality." 


THE   ATOMIC    VIEW    OF   NATURE. 


433 


brought  about  by  the  development  of  the  so-called  kinetic 
theory  of  gases  in  the  second  half  of  the  century.  This  is 
a  physical,  not  a  chemical,  theory. 

The  kinetic  theory  of  gases,  invented  for  the  purpose 
of  explaining  the  pressure  which  all  bodies  in  the  gaseous 
state  exert  on  the  walls  of  the  containing  vessels,  will 
always  be  identified  with  the  two  names  of  Clausius  in 
Germany  and  Clerk  Maxwell  in  England.1  But  if  we 


1  Before  the  atomic  view  of  matter 
had,  in  the  course  of  the  last  fifty 
years,  closely  and  definitely  allied 
itself  with  the  kinetic  view,  it  had 
been  allied  with  the  astronomical 
view  of  matter.  In  the  last  cen- 
tury and  the  earlier  decades  of 
the  present  century  we  frequently 
find  the  behaviour  of  a  complex 
of  molecules  or  atoms  compared 
with  that  of  a  planetary  system  ; 
but  in  addition  to  the  forces  of 
attraction,  those  of  repulsion  had 
to  be  resorted  to  in  order  to  ex- 
plain the  expansiveness  of  gases. 
Heat  was  then  considered  to  be  a 
material  substance,  the  particles  of 
which  repelled  each  other.  Dalton 
favoured  this  view  in  the  introduc- 
tion to  his  'New  System  of  Chemical 
Philosophy ' ;  so  did  Berthollet  and 
most  of  the  French  physicists  who 
were  brought  up  in  the  school  of 
Newton  and  Laplace.  Lasswitz,  in 
his  '  Geschichte  der  Atomistik '  (2 
vols.,  Hamburg,  1890),  has  traced 
the  '  Decline  of  Kinetic  Atomism  '  in 
the  seventeenth  century  under  the 
influence  of  the  '  Corpuscular  Philo- 
sophy.' The  kinetic  view  of  matter 
was  allied  with  the  Cartesian  physi- 
cal philosophy,  which  was  dispelled 
by  Newtonianism  in  France  and  by 
Kant's  philosophy  in  Germany.  In 
consequence,  when  in  Germany  A. 
Kronig  published  his  '  Grundziige 
einer  Theorie  der  Gase'  in  1856, 
philosophers  who  had  been  speculat- 
ing in  the  direction  of  a  Newtonian 

VOL.  I. 


atomism  (see  Fechner's  '  Atomen- 
lehre,'1855 ;  Redtenbacher's  'Dyna- 
miden  System,'  1857  ;  and  other 
publications  quoted  by  Rosenberger, 
'  Geschichte  der  Physik,'  vol.  iii.  p. 
536,  &c.)  were  much  taken  by  sur- 
prise. It  had  the  immediate  result 
of  inducing  R.  Clausius,  who  had 
been  occupied  with  similar  re- 
searches since  1850,  to  publish  his 
celebrated  memoir,  'Ueber  die  Art 
der  Bewegung  welche  wir  Warme 
nennen '  (Poggendorf's  '  Annalen,' 
vol.  c.,  1857).  These  two  publica- 
tions first  called  general  attention 
to  the  subject.  Joule's  paper, 
which  appeared  in  the  '  Memoirs  of 
the  Lit.  and  Phil.  Soc.  of  Man- 
chester,' had  remained  unnoticed, 
but  was  reprinted  by  him,  at  the 
request  of  Clausius,  in  the  '  Philoso- 
phical Magazine '  (4th  ser.  vol.  xiv.) 
in  1857.  Subsequently,  the  re- 
searches of  Paul  du  Bois-Reymond 
and  others  unearthed  a  whole  list 
of  authors  who,  in  more  or  less 
definite  ways,  had  resorted  to  the 
hypothesis  of  a  rectilinear  trans- 
latory  motion  of  the  molecules  in 
order  to  explain  the  phenomena  of 
pressure  and  other  properties  of 
gases.  Among  these,  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli (in  his  '  Hydrodynamica,' 
1738)  seems  to  have  expressed  the 
clearest  views,  and  he  is  now  usu- 
ally named  as  the  father  of  the 
hypothesis.  The  fullest  statement 
of  the  historical  data  will  be  found 
in  the  posthumous  second  edition  of 

2  E 


434  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

agree  to  date  the  real  birth,  not  the  incubation,  of  any 
scientific  idea  from  the  moment  when  it  was  set  forth 
in  definite  figures,  and  with  mathematical  precision  per- 
mitting of  a  precise  verification  by  actual  test,  the  modern 
theory  of  gases  was  born  in  Manchester  in  the  school 
34.  of  Dalton,  when  Joule  in  1857  actually  calculated  the 

Joule's  cal- 
culations,     velocity  with  which  a  particle  of  hydrogen  at  ordinary 

atmospheric  pressure  and  temperature  must  be  moving, 
assuming  that  this  atmospheric  pressure  is  equilibrated  by 
the  rectilinear  motion  and  impact  of  the  supposed  particles 
t>f  the  gas  on  each  other  and  the  walls  of  the  containing 
vessel.  This  meant  taking  the  atomic  view  of  matter  in 
real  earnest,  not  merely  symbolically,  as  chemists  had  done. 
Joule  gave  up  the  older  and  vague  ideas  of  a  rotatory  or  a 
vibratory  motion  of  the  particles  of  a  gas  which  had  been 
floating  about  since  the  time  of  Hooke1  in  various  theories, 
and  adopted  the  suggestion  of  Daniel  Bernoulli,  known  to 
him  through  Herapath,  that  all  particles  of  gaseous  matter 
are  in  a  natural  state  of  rectilinear  motion,  which  is 
changed  only  by  the  encounter  with  other  particles  or  by 
the  walls  of  the  containing  vessel  on  which  they  impinge, 
and  from  which  they  rebound.2 

Clausius,  '  Die  mechanische  Warme-  <   the  correct  one,  and  that  Newtonian 

theorie'   (Braunschweig,   1889-91,  i   (attracting    and    repelling)    forces 

p.  2,  &c.)     See  also  0.  E.   Mayer,  play  only  a  subordinate,  if  any,  part 

'  Die  kinetische  Theorie  der  Case '  j   in    the    observable    phenomena    of 

(2nded.,  Breslau,  1895, parti,  p.  11).  gaseous  bodies,  is  based  upon  Joule 

1  See  Tait,  'Properties  of  Matter.'  and  Thomson's  experiments  made 
2nd  ed.,  p.   289,  also  J.  P.  Joule's  in   1853.       It   belongs   to   quite   a 
Memoir  on  '  Heat  and  the  Constitu-  different  line  of  reasoning,  neither 
tion   of  Elastic   Fluids,'    1848,  re-  chemical  nor  mechanical,  but  going 
printed  in  '  Scientific  Papers,'  vol.  upon  the  principle  introduced  into 
i.  p.  290,  Ac.  scientific  thought  about  the  middle 

2  The  real  proof  that  the  kinetic,  of  the  century,  that  heat  and  work 
in  contradistinction  to  what  we  may  are  convertible  terms  and  equivalent 
call   the   Newtonian,    view   of   the  quantities.      Now,  it  was  generally 
motion  of  the  molecules  of  a  gas  is  assumed,  before  Joule  and  Thomson 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE. 


435 


This  idea  of  the  rectilinear  motion  of  the  particles  of 
matter  in  a  free,  i.e.,  a  gaseous,  state  (the  first  attempt  to 
explain  the  physical  properties  of  matter  by  giving  a 
numerical  value  to  a  molecular,  not  molar,  quantity)  was 
not  regarded  by  chemists,  for  it  was  indeed  of  little  use  in 
explaining  chemical  combinations  and  reactions.  It,  how-  35. 

.  Clausius's 

ever,  very  soon  received  an  important  addition  under  the  firs 
treatment  of  Clausius.1 

The  kinetic  theory  of  gases  had  not  been  propounded 
for  the  purpose  of  explaining  chemical  phenomena;  it 
had  grown  out  of  repeated  attempts  to  explain  the  nature 
of  heat,  and  the  fact,  established  about  ten  years  earlier 
by  Mayer  and  Joule,  that  heat  can  be  transformed  into 
the  mechanical  energy  of  molar  motion.  The  idea  sug- 
gested itself  that  if  heat  can  disappear  and  be  replaced 
by  the  measurable  motion  of  molar  (measurably  large) 
masses,  and  vice  versd,  heat  itself  may  be  merely  the 
energy  of  the  directly  immeasurable  movements  of  mole- 
cular (immeasurably  small)  masses ;  and  as  every  body 


made  their  careful  experiments, 
that  if  gaseous  bodies  were  allowed 
to  expand,  without  doing  work, 
iJo  change  of  temperature  took 
place — i.e.,  that  heat  neither  ap- 
peared nor  disappeared.  This  would 
mean  that  no  work  of  either  repel- 
ling or  attracting  forces  was  done. 
Joule  and  Thomson  showed  that 
there  was  indeed  a  very  slight  cool- 
ing, indicating  that  a  small  amount 
of  heat  or  energy  was  used  up  in 
doing  work  against  attracting  forces 
— the  forces  of  cohesion.  Had  re- 
pelling forces  existed,  their  work 
would  have  shown  itself  in  a  rise  of 
temperature.  This  line  of  reason- 
ing will  occupy  us  in  a  subsequent 
chapter  (see  0.  E.  Meyer,  '  Theorie 
der  Gase,'  vol.  i.  p.  7,  &c. ,  also 


Joule's  'Scientific  Papers,'  vol.  ii. 
p.   216,  &c.) 

1  How  little  chemical  and  physical 
reasoning  went  hand  in  hand  before 
the  middle  of  the  century  is  seen 
from  the  fact  that  only  after  Clau- 
sius had  published  his  first  paper 
(see  note,  p.  433),  in  which  he  came 
to  the  conclusion  that  the  molecules 
or  smallest  physical  particles  of 
simple  (elementary)  substances  con- 
sist of  several  atoms,  was  his  atten- 
tion drawn  to  the  fact  that  some 
French  chemists,  notably  Dumas, 
Laurent,  and  Gerhard t,  had  already, 
by  different  arguments,  arrived  at 
the  conclusion  that  the  molecules 
of  simple  (elementary)  gases  consist 
of  several  atoms  (see  Clausius,  loc. 
tit.,  p.  22,  &c.) 


436  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

in  the  gaseous  state  shows  the  mechanical  energy  which 
we  call  pressure  or  expansiveness,  the  attempt  was  made 
to  explain  the  phenomena  of  expansion,  pressure,  and 
temperature  of  gases  by  a  purely  mechanical  hypothesis. 
This  answered  remarkably  well.  On  the  assumption  that 
the  particles  of  a  perfect  gas  possess  a  rectilinear  motion, 
the  experimental  formula1  of  Boyle  and  Mariotte,  of  Dai- 
ton,  and  of  Gay-Lussac,  could  be  theoretically  deduced. 
It  also  became  evident  that  under  this  conception  the 
forgotten  statement  of  Avogadro  must  be  correct,  accord- 
ing to  which  equal  volumes  of  different  gases,  under  equal 
pressures  and  at  equal  temperatures,  contain  an  equal 
number  of  freely  moving  particles. 

se.  And  when   Clausius   showed  further   that  in  perfect 

energy  of      gases  only  a  portion  of  the  quantities  of  energy  which 

molecules. 

are  measured  as  motion  or  as  heat  can  be  explained 
by  the  assumed  rectilinear  motion  of  the  particles  of 
gases,  and  that  an  internal  motion  of  the  particles  them- 
selves must  be  assumed,  the  new  ideas  became  still  more 
exactly  defined ;  they  included  the  conception  familiar  to 
chemists  of  compound  atoms  or  molecules.  The  smallest 
individual  particles  of  matter  in  the  free  state  were  them- 
selves not  simple  bodies,  but  systems  of  still  smaller 
particles ;  they  were  molecules  composed  of  atoms  ;  the 
symbols  of  chemists  became  descriptive  of  real  physical 
conditions ;  the  vague  notions  of  radicles,  types,  or  com- 
pound atoms  began  to  acquire  geometrical  and  mechanical 
definiteness. 

Thus  the  atomic  theory,  known  to  the  ancients,  revived 
by  Daltori  in  the  early  years  of  the  century,  and  em- 
ployed by  chemical  philosophers  for  half  a  century  as  a 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF   NATURE. 


437 


convenient  symbolism,  had,  about  the  year  1860,  been 

.    .  ,  , 

accepted  by  physicists,  and  used  not  merely  as  a  con- 
venient  symbolism,  but  as  a  physical  reality. 

Joule  had  actually  calculated  the  velocity  of  a  particle 
of  hydrogen  gas.  The  atomic  view  of  nature  was  now 
taken  in  real  earnest.  To  establish  it  still  further,  there 
were  required  definite  numerical  data  l  as  to  the  size  of 
the  smallest  particles  (henceforth  sometimes  called  atoms, 
sometimes  more  correctly  molecules)  and  their  number, 
and  also  clearer  views  as  to  the  composition  of  the  mole- 
cules out  of  their  elements,  the  chemical  atoms. 

The  interest  which  attaches  to  this  latest  development 
of  the  atomic  theory  is  very  great  :  it  has  brought  about 
a  union  of  the  researches  of  chemists  and  physicists,  and 
has  made  chemistry  a  province  of  natural  philosophy.2  No 
one  has  done  more  than  the  late  Professor  Clerk  Max- 


37. 

The  atomic 

theory  ac- 


186°* 


1  Numerical  data  regarding  the 
size  and  number  of  smallest  physi- 
cal particles  contained  in  a  given 
volume  of  matter  have  been  sup- 
plied by  various  methods  or  various 
"lines  of  reasoning."  The  best 
summary  will  be  found  in  Lord 
Kelvin's  lecture,  "  On  the  Size  of 
Atoms  "  (1883  :  reprinted  in  '  Pop- 
ular Lectures  and  Addresses,'  vol. 
i.  p.  147  877.)  The  four  lines  of 
reasoning  are  founded  on  the  un- 
dulatory  theory  of  light,  on  the 
phenomena  of  contact  electricity, 
on  capillary  attraction,  and  on  the 
kinetic  theory  of  gases.  They 
"  agree  in  showing  that  the  mole- 
cules of  ordinary  matter  must  be 
something  like  the  one  ten -mil- 
lionth, or  from  the  one  ten -mil- 
lionth to  the  one  hundred-millionth 
of  a  centimetre  in  diameter." 

2  "  We  can  distinguish  two  kinds 
of  motion,  atomic  motion  and  mole- 
cular motion.  ...  To  this  dis- 


tinction corresponds  the  division 
of  natural  philosophy  into  physics 
and  chemistry,  not  rigidly,  yet  in 
so  far  as  chemistry  is  mainly  oc- 
cupied with  the  equilibrium  of  the 
atoms,  physics  with  the  mechanics 
of  the  molecules.  Chemical  equil- 
ibrium, unchanged  condition  of  the 
molecules,  exists  if  the  affinity 
which  holds  together  the  atoms 
equilibrates  the  forces  which  tend 
to  loosen  the  composition  of  the 
molecule :  these  forces  consist  in 
the  motion  of  the  atoms.  .  .  .  As 
accordingly  in  a  chemically  stable 
compound  the  atomic  motions  re- 
main in  lasting  dynamical  equil- 
ibrium with  the  chemical  forces,  .  . . 
there  remains  for  the  examination 
of  the  purely  physical  phenomena 
in  the  first  instance  only  the  mole- 
cular movements "  (0.  E.  Meyer, 
'  Die  kinetische  Theorie  der  Gase,' 
vol.  i.  p.  6). 


438 


SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 


38. 

Clerk  Max- 
well.   The 
statistical 
view  of 
nature. 


well  to  develop  the  novel  conceptions  which  here  force 
themselves  upon  us.  Especially  are  we  indebted  to  him 
for  the  idea — marking  an  epoch  in  the  history  of  scientific 
thought — of  the  difference  between  historical  knowledge 
of  natural  phenomena  and  a  merely  statistical  summary 
of  average  results.1  If  the  atomic  view  of  nature  has  to 
be  adopted  seriously,  as  the  development  of  the  kinetic 


1  See   Clerk   Maxwell's   memoir, 
'  Illustrations    of    the    Dynamical 
Theory  of  Gases'  (1859:  reprinted 
in  'Scientific  Papers,'  vol.  i.  p.  377). 
Clausius  had  in  his  second  paper, 
' '  On  the  average  mean  path  of  a 
particle  "  (Poggendorf 's  '  Annalen,' 
1858),  given  an  expression  for  this 
quantity  as  depending  on  the  aver- 
age distance  of  two  particles  and  on 
the  average  diameter  of  the  sphere 
of  action  of  a  particle.     As  these 
quantities  are  all  only  mean  or  aver- 
agequantities.hehad  been  obliged  to 
resort  to  a  method  which  was  then 
novel  in  physical  science,  the  method 
of  averages  and  the  calculus  of  prob- 
ability, which  is  its  mathematical 
expression.     He  had  calculated  the 
probability  of  a  certain  motion  of  a 
particle.    Maxwell,  who  had  in  1856 
been  engaged  in  writing  his  Adams 
prize  essay  "  On  the  stability  of  the 
motion  of  Saturn's  rings,"  had  there 
considered  the  possibility  of  these 
rings  being  composed  of  a  cloud  of 
scattered  particles  moving  with  all 
possible    velocities    towards     each 
other  and   round    some  attracting 
centre  :  he  was  thus  familiar  with 
physical    problems    in    which    the 
given  data  could  be  only  average 
quantities.     He  now  undertook  to 
develop  systematically  the  methods 
necessary  for  treating  such   prob- 
lems, of  which  we  have  only  statis- 
tical knowledge,   and  he  there  de- 
veloped his  famous  law  which  gives 
the  distribution  of  different  veloci- 
ties in  a  crowd  of  particles  moving 


at  random  and  in  their  collisions 
obeying  the  condition  of  the  con- 
servation of  energy.     This  investi- 
gation marks  an  epoch  in  mathe- 
matical physics  and  in  the  history 
of  the  atomic  view  of  nature.    Like 
all    theorems    connected   with   the 
theory  of  probability,  it  has  pro- 
voked a  large  literature,  the  founda- 
tions of  the  proof  and  the  different 
steps  in  the  logic  of  the  deductions 
having  been  examined  and  criticised 
in  the  most  searching  manner.    The 
expression   given   by   Maxwell   has 
stood  all  these  criticisms, — "  he  has 
demonstrated     the     possibility    of 
calculating  in  a  strict  manner  the 
averages  which  before  him  had  only 
been    estimated,    but    which    were 
required  for  a  further  development 
of  the  theory  of  gases."     See  0.  E. 
Meyer,  '  Die  kinetische  Theorie  der 
Gase,'  2nd  eel.,  vol.  i.  p.  45,  &c.,  where 
also  a  complete  account  is  given  of 
the    various    steps    by    which    the 
doubts  which  attached  to  Maxwell's 
theories    and    his    proofs    were    at 
length  removed,  and  the  "variety 
of    traps    and    pit  -  falls "    avoided 
"which  are  met  with  even  in  the 
elements  of  the  subject"  (see  Tait, 
"On  the  Foundations  of  the  Kinetic 
Theory  of  Gases,"  'Trans,  of  the 
Royal   Soc.    of    Edinburgh,'   1886, 
vol.   xxxiii.  part  1,  p.   66).      In  a 
later  chapter  of  this  history  I  in- 
tend to  trace  the  development  of 
the  statistical  view  of  nature,  and 
shall  then  have  occasion  to  revert 
to  this  subject. 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE.       439 

theory  of  gases  suggests,  we  begin  to  realise  the  enormous 
numbers  of  individual  elements  of  matter  with  which  we 
have  to  do  in  any  physical  or  chemical  operation  or  ex- 
periment. The  step  which  enabled  mathematicians  to 
calculate  molar  and  cosmical  phenomena  by  looking  upon 
them  as  made  up  of  an  immeasurably,  nay  infinitely,  large 
number  of  elementary  parts,  be  these  of  space  or  time, 
was  taken  by  Newton  and  Leibniz :  its  result  was  the 
invention,  development,  and  application  of  the  infinitesi- 
mal calculus.  Our  fundamental  notions  applied  only  to 
integrals,  to  a  summation  of  these  differential  properties. 
It  was  the  problem  of  the  new  calculus  to  deduce  from 
the  simple  differential  properties,  expressed  in  what  is 
called  the  differential  equation,  the  results  of  finite  ob- 
servable quantities.  This  was  done  by  a  process  of  sum- 
mation or  integration.  In  this  process  the  elements  were, 
however,  all  considered  to  be  equal.  This  was  an  assump- 
tion which,  for  the  purposes  of  simplicity,  might  be  safely 
made  in  a  first  approximation.  When,  however,  the  kin- 
etic theory  of  gases  took  seriously  into  account  the  motion, 
velocity,  number,  and  size  of  the  constituent  particles  of 
matter  contained  in  any  finite  measurable  volume,  or  por- 
tion of  matter,  two  distinct  views  presented  themselves  : 
the  one  which  looks  only  at  the  total  or  average  result 
and  aspect  of  the  phenomena,  the  other  which  looks  at 
the  actual  behaviour  and  properties  of  the  component 
parts,  be  these  ever  so  numerous  or  ever  so  small.  These 
latter  could  no  longer  be  regarded  as  differentials  which 
lose  their  independent  existence  in  the  process  of  summa- 
tion :  they  had  individual  properties,  which  were  not  lost 
in  the  aggregate.  It  is  evident  that  chemists  had  been 


*  440  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

studying  those  properties  of  matter  that  are  preserved 
distinct  in  ever  so  large  a  number  of  individuals  which 
are  characteristically  and  specifically  alike :  while  physi- 
cists had  been  mainly  studying  the  properties  of  distance, 
motion,  velocity,  and  size,  which,  if  added  together,  merge 
themselves  into  a  common  sum,  integral  or  average.  It 
does  not  follow  that,  even  so  far  as  these  latter  proper- 
ties are  concerned,  the  numberless  individual  particles  of 
matter  behave  alike ;  their  sizes,  velocities,  and  move- 
ments may  be  very  different :  indeed  it  is  evident  that, 
in  a  large  crowd  of  moving  particles,  they  must  be  widely 
different. 

39.  In  assigning  numbers  to  these  data,  it  was  therefore 

averages.  clear  that  only  average  or  mean  values  could  be  meant, 
and  that  our  actual  physical  knowledge  of  the  individual 
elements  resembles  that  statistical  information  which  we 
possess,  for  instance,  regarding  the  mortality,  average 
age,  and  general  properties  and  ways  of  the  members 
of  a  great  population.  It  is  statistical  knowledge,  it  is 
not  individual,  historical,  or  biographical  knowledge,  that 
we  possess. 

The  individual  behaviour  of  the  single  molecules,  their 
sizes,  their  velocities,  the  length  of  their  paths,  their  vibra- 
tions, rotations,  and  internal  motions,  remain  unknown. 
What  can  be  known  is  only  the  average  magnitudes  of 
these  quantities,  and  possibly  the  extreme  limits  within 
which  these  individual  magnitudes  vary.  The  great  dif- 
ferences exhibited  by  larger  portions  of  different  kinds 
of  matter — i.e.,  the  chemical  differences  or  qualities — were 
reduced  to  the  actual  composition  and  qualities  of  the 
molecules  and  atoms  themselves.  Chemists  and  physi- 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OP  NATURE.       441 

cists  were  now  alike  compelled  to  venture  on  some  more 
definite  hypothesis,  descriptive  of  the  great  variety  of 
constitution  which  the  molecules  of  chemically  distinct 
substances  exhibit.  These  molecules  show  in  their  com- 
bining numbers,  and  in  their  physical  properties,  great 
fixity,  excluding  apparently  all  gradual  transitions.  The 
manner  in  which  they  enter  into,  and  again  separate  out 
of,  combinations  and  compounds,  always  regaining  and 
showing  their  original  characteristics,  forced  more  and 
more  upon  natural  philosophers  the  conviction  that  com- 
pounds were  merely  geometrical  arrangements  of  indi-  40. 

.  Geometrical 

vidually  independent  atoms,  and  that  these  atoms  must  arrangement 

of  atoms. 

possess  geometrically  different  forms  and  figures,  enabling 
them,  without  loss  of  their  individuality,  to  enter  into 
varying  configurations. 

The  conception  of  the  molecule  as  a  system  of  atoms, 
geometrically  arranged,  had  gradually  grown  from  vague 
suggestions  in  the  minds  of  physicists  as  well  as  chemists 
— i.e.,  of  students  of  the  quantitative  as  well  as  of  those 
of  the  qualitative  properties  of  substances.  To  the  former 
it  was  especially  the  forms  of  crystals,  to  the  latter  the 
different  degrees  of  saturation  of  chemical  substances, 
that  suggested  a  geometrical  arrangement  of  atoms  as 
the  constitution  of  the  smallest  particles  or  molecules 
of  different  substances. 

Ever  since  the  study  of  the  regular  forms  of  minerals        «. 

Crystallo- 

or  of   artificially  prepared  crystals  was   reduced   to   an  graphy. 
exact   science   by  the   labours  of   Haiiy,  at  the  end  of 
the   last    century,1    the   forms   of    these    regular  shapes 
have  been  valued  by  investigators,  for  two  distinct  rea- 

1  See  above,  chapter  i.  p.  116. 


442  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

sons.  They  seemed  to  afford  a  practical  means  of  recog- 
nising and  obtaining  in  the  laboratory  substances  in 
their  qualitative  or  chemical  purity,  if  they  were  ele- 
ments, or  in  identical  chemical  combinations,  if  they 
were  compounds.  And  secondly,  these  regular,  recur- 
ring forms,  which,  in  many  cases,  exhibited  characteristic 
and  geometrically  fixed  arrangements  of  plane  surfaces, 
appeared  the  only  means  by  which  we  could  gain  an 
insight  into  the  grouping  and  the  shape  of  the  ultimate 
particles,  out  of  which,  according  to  the  atomic  view, 
molar  substances  were  constituted.  If  the  particles  of 
any  substance,  when  set  free  to  follow  their  most  natural 
movements  by  solution,  by  fusion,  or  by  volatilisation, 
meet  again  during  the  process  of  solidification  in  definite, 
always  recurring  forms,  the  conclusion  seems  obvious 
that  the  individual  and  ultimate  particles  possess 
marked  peculiarities  in  the  different  directions  of  space. 
And  it  is  almost  inconceivable  that  these  peculiarities 
should  consist  in  anything  else  than  in  distinct  primitive 
forms,  arranged  in  varying,  but  geometrically  definable, 
meshes  of  a  network.  Accordingly,  different  systems 
have  been  elaborated  ever  since  the  age  of  Haliy,  which 
have  the  object  of  easily  classifying,  recognising,  and 
measuring  crystalline  structures,  or,  more  ambitiously, 
of  discovering  the  number  of  simple  forms  and  arrange- 
ments of  networks  of  which  our  spatial  conceptions 
admit.  It  is  satisfactory  to  be  able  to  state  that 
investigations  of  the  latter  kind,  carried  on  from 
seemingly  different  beginnings,  have  resulted  in  the 
recognition  of  a  certain  limited  number  of  forms  of 
symmetry.  This  symmetry  is  referred  to  points,  called 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


443 


centres,  or  to  lines,  called  axes,  or  to  planes  of  sym- 
metry.1 French  and  German  investigators  have  deduced 
in  different  ways  the  different  possible  forms  of  sym- 
metry, and  have  shown  that  in  all  thirty-two  different 
forms  of  symmetry  or  groups  are  geometrically  possible. 
These  thirty-two  fundamental  groups  of  crystals  can  be 
gathered  up  into  six  classes  or  types,  according  to  the 
different  systems  of  crystallographic  axes  or  the  number 
of  planes  of  symmetry  belonging  to  them.2 


1  The  question  may  be  raised, 
to  what  extent  crystallography  is 
obliged  to  assume  a  molecular 
structure  of  matter,  or  what  sup- 
port does  the  atomic  view  receive 
from  it  ?  On  this  point  see  Ost- 
wald's  '  Allgemeine  Chemie,'  vol.  i. 
p.  855,  &c.  The  geometrical  forms 
of  crystals  can  either  be  derived 
from  elementary  polyhedra,  as  Haiiy 
attempted  to  do  by  his  "  molecules 
integrantes "  and  his  theory  of 
decrescences,  space  being  in  this 
system  considered  as  continuously 
filled  ;  or  the  elementary  particles 
may  be  considered  to  consist  of 
meshes  of  points  geometrically  ar- 
ranged in  the  corners  of  a  primitive 
figure  in  three  dimensions  ;  or  ele- 
mentary spheres  or  ellipsoids  may 
be  supposed  to  be  piled  on  each 
other  likecannon-balls.  The  two  lat- 
ter systems  assume  vacant  spaces  ; 
the  first  view  refers  the  crystalline 
shape  to  some  primitive  crystal,  and, 
therefore,  does  not  explain  it.  It 
has  accordingly  been  said  that  "  the 
structure  of  crystals  is  one  of  the 
principal  supports  of  the  molecular 
theory.  In  assuming  continuous 
matter  without  at  least  points 
which  are  geometrically  or  kine- 
matically  distinct,  the  anisotropic 
structure  of  crystals  is  quite  un- 
thinkable" (Lehmann,  'Molecular- 
physik,'  vol.  ii.  p.  376).  This  view 
does  not  agree  with  what  Ostwald 


says  ('Allgemeine  Chemie,'  vol.  i.  p. 
868)  ;  he  considers  that  the  struc- 
ture of  crystals  affords  no  proof 
for  the  molecular  constitution  of 
matter,  as  the  data  of  elasticity 
by  no  means  necessarily  require 
a  molecular  arrangement,  but  for- 
mally can  be  ascribed  as  easily  to 
continuous  matter.  "  Nevertheless 
the  molecular  view  has  the  advan- 
tage of  greater  evidence,  and  leads 
to  the  same  results  with  much 
greater  simplicity,  and  hence  more 
convincingly."  It  seems,  however, 
that  if  chemical  facts  and  physical 
theory  force  upon  us  the  atomic 
view,  crystallographic  phenomena 
force  us  to  complete  it  by  some 
conception  of  geometrical  arrange- 
ments. 

-  This  purely  geometrical  treat- 
ment was  introduced  by  Bravais 
in  his  '  Etudes  crystallograph- 
iques'  (1851),  the  much  earlier 
work  of  Hessel  ('  Krystallometrie,' 
1831)  having  been  forgotten.  It 
was  further  developed  by  L.  Sohnke 
('  Entwickelung  der  Theorie  der 
Krystallstructur, '  1879),  and  com- 
pleted by  Curie  (1884)  and  Min- 
nigerode  (1886).  A  concise  sum- 
mary will  be  found  in  Liebisch, 
'  Physikalische  Krystallographie, ' 
Leipzig,  1891,  pp.  3  to  50 ;  also 
Groth,  '  Physikalische  Krystallo- 
graphie,' Leipzig,  1895,  p.  324, 
&c. 


444  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

42.  An  analogy  has  been  pointed  out l  between  the  atomic 

Analogy 

between  theory  in  chemistry,  by  which  Dalton  explained  the  fixed 
atomicCiaws  simple  and  multiple  proportions  of  the  combining  weights 
of  various  substances,  and  the  molecular  theory  of  crystal- 
line structures,  by  which  the  fundamental  forms  of  crystals 
are  defined  and  the  accessory  forms  derived  from  them. 
It  has  been  found  that  if  once  a  crystal  has  been  defined 
by  a  fundamental  plane  referred  to  three  axes  at  fixed 
angles,  all  other  planes  or  faces  can  be  defined  by  simple 
multiples  of  the  numbers  which  belong  to  the  fundamental 
plane,  and  which  are  called  the  parameters  of  the  crystal. 
This  fundamental  rule  or  law  of  crystallisation,  termed  by 
Haiiy  the  law  of  derivation,  stands  thus  in  the  same  rela- 
tion to  the  corpuscular  theory  of  the  structure  of  bodies 
as  the"  law  of  fixed  multiple  proportions  stands  to  the 
original  atomic  view  of  matter,  and  it  is  thought  that  it 
may  in  the  future  lead  to  important  results.2 

43.  Another  very  remarkable  discovery  had  been  made  by 
pnism.         Mitscherlich  in  1823.3    This  is  the  property  which  various 

compounds  possess  of  crystallising  in  the  same  forms, 
although  they  contain  different  elements — such  elements 
being,  however,  joined  together  by  similar  formulae.  The 
elements  are,  as  it  were,  interchangeable.  This  phe- 


1  See      Ostwald,      "  Allgemeine 
Chemie,'  vol.  i.  p.  870. 

2  A  question  arises  in  this  connec- 


a  somewhat  disturbed  manner"  (loc. 
cit.,  vol.  i.  p.  890).  This  I  under- 
stand to  mean  that,  if  disturbing 


tion  as  to  the  accuracy  of  the  crys-   j   circumstances   could    be    removed, 

tallographic  law  of  the  fixity  of  the  the  law  of  the  fixity  of  angles  and 

angles.     In  respect  of  this  Ostwald  the  simple  multiples  of  the  indices 

says :  "  On  examining  the  validity  would  obtain  with  the  same  accur- 

of  the  fundamental  laws  of  crystallo-  acy  as  do  the  combining  numbers 

graphy,   it    becomes    evident    that  and    their    multiples    in    chemical 

they  are  only  approximate,  or  per-  combinations. 

haps  more  correctly,  that  there  exist  3  See  supra,  chap.  ii.  p.  191  and 

numerous  circumstances  which  per-  note, 
mit  them  to  show  themselves  only  in 


THE   ATOMIC    VIEW    OF    NATURE. 


445 


nomenon  has  been  called  isomorphism.  The  discovery 
has  been  of  great  practical  value,  as  well  as  theoretical 
interest.  If  the  definite  and  invariable  form  of  existence 
which  the  crystal  exhibits  is  considered  as  a  proof  of  the 
purity  of  a  chemical  substance,  and  if  in  the  same  crystal 
one  elementary  substance  can  be  replaced  by  one  or  several 
other  substances,  then  this  substitution  must  take  place  in 
definite  proportions  of  weight,  in  the  equivalent  propor- 
tions. Thus  the  production  of  such  isomorphous  crystals 
affords  a  method  of  determining  the  relative  atomic 
weights  or  equivalents.  As  such  it  was  hailed  by  Ber- 
zelius ;  the  more  so,  as  in  no  case  did  the  equivalents 
thus  obtained  contradict  the  numbers  he  had  found  by 
other  methods.1  Theoretically,  the  property  of  isomor- 
phism acquired  a  still  greater  interest  when  Mitscher- 


1  In  the  early  days  of  the  atomic 
theory  as  developed  by  Berzelius, 
great  uncertainty  existed  as  to  the 
numbers  which  were  to  be  chosen  for 
the  atomic  weights  of  the  elements. 
This  was  owing  to  the  property  of 
fixed  multiple  ratios — it  remaining 
undecided  which  was  the  smallest 
submultiple  of  a  given  combining 
ratio  in  which  any  special  element 
could  enter  into  combination. 
Other  methods  were  then  used  to 
assist  in  deciding  this  point.  The 
law  of  volumes,  and  later  the  pro- 
perties of  isomorphism,  were  there- 
fore hailed  by  Berzelius  as  welcome 
aids  in  fixing  the  atomic  numbers. 
Both  these  methods  are  still  used, 
though  the  latter  is  not  always  de- 
cisive. The  most  important  method 
according  to  the  present  state  of  our 
knowledge  is  the  determination  of 
the  vapour  density,  where  such  can 
be  got,  and  that  of  the  specific  heat 
in  the  solid  state.  It  is  mainly 
owing  to  Cannizzaro  (1858)  that 


the  apparent  contradictions,  which 
were  supposed  to  exist  in  the  num- 
bers arrived  at  by  various  methods, 
were  explained  by  reverting  to 
Avogadro's  forgotten  hypothesis. 
The  periodic  law  or  arrangement  of 
the  elements  into  classes  showing 
similar  physical  properties  is  like- 
wise of  use.  A  complete,  lucid, 
and  exhaustive  statement  of  the 
most  recent  position  of  our  know- 
ledge of  the  true  atomic  weights 
of  the  elements  will  be  found  in 
Lothar  Meyer's  posthumous  tract, 
'  Die  Atome  und  ihre  Eigenschaf- 
ten,'  Breslau,  1896.  In  this  valuable 
book,  as  also  in  Ostwald's  '  Allge- 
meine  Cheniie,'  vol.  i.,  will  also  be 
found  an  account  of  the  degree  of  ac- 
curacy which  attaches  to  our  present 
knowledge  of  the  atomic  and  com- 
bining numbers,  which  form  the 
solid  foundation  of  all  quantitative 
chemistry  and  all  practical  applica- 
tions. 


446  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

lich  discovered  another  crystalline  property  of  certain 
chemically  pure  substances.  He  found  that  some  sub- 
stances can  crystallise  in  more  than  one  distinct  and 
definite  form.  The  alums  and  vitriols  are  typical  of  iso- 
44.  morphism.  As  typical  of  the  second  property,  which  was 
phison.  termed  by  him  dimorphism  or  polymorphism,  we  have 
the  well-known  mineral  ealc-spar,  which  is  dimorphous 
with  aragonite,  both  having  the  same  chemical  constitution 
and  properties.  A  typical  example  of  dimorphism  is  the 
mineral  rutile,  which  is  chemically  the  same  substance  as 
the  mineral  anatase,  both  being  chemically  pure  titanic 
oxide.  Among  the  elements,  pure  sulphur  crystallises  in 
two  different  forms.  The  property  of  dimorphism  seemed 
at  first  to  contradict  the  inference  which  Mitseherlich  had 
drawn  from  his  first  discovery — viz.,  that  the  crystalline 
shape  is  expressive  of  the  number  and  chemical  connec- 
tion of  the  smallest  particles  or  atoms ;  but  the  further 
discovery,  that  if  of  two  isomorphous  bodies  one  is  dimor- 
phous, the  other  is  likewise  so,  gave  again  a  great  support 
to  the  geometrical  conception  of  atomic  complexes — i.e., 
to  the  idea  that  chemical  individuality  is  ultimately  to  be 
explained  not  only  by  the  number,  but  also  by  the  mutual 
fixed  position  and  shape,  of  the  atoms.  .  And  yet  it  seemed 
a  long  way,  and  is  a  long  way  still,  from  the  external, 
visible,  and  well-marked  shape  of  a  crystal,  with  its 
peculiar  and  well-defined  geometrical,  elastic,  optical,  and 
thermal  properties,  to  the  primitive  molecule,  made  up  of 
still  more  simple  atoms,  in  the  form,  number,  and  arrange- 
ment of  which  we  are  again  and  again  tempted  to  see  the 
nature  of  chemical  or  qualitative  individuality.  To  obtain 
a  clear  view  in  this  way  would  be  to  work  our  way  from 


THE   ATOMIC    VIEW   OF   NATURE.  447 

outside  inward — a  method  which  has  rarely  led  to  definite 
results  in  scientific  research. 

A   department   of  chemical   science   called  structural        45. 

i  i'ii  11-11  Structural 

chemistry — which    has    quite    recently    developed    into  and  stereo- 
chemistry. 

stereo-chemistry — has  during  the  last  fifty  years  of  the 
century  been  working  by  the  opposite  method.  Even 
those  organic  chemists  who  ridiculed  the  notion  that 
a  chemical  formula,  which  on  the  surface  of  the  paper 
on  which  it  is  written  cannot  help  making  use  of 
geometrical  position  and  proximities,  is  in  any  way  a 
picture  of  the  arrangements  of  atoms  in  real  space,  were 
nevertheless  forced  to  avail  themselves  of  this  symbolism. 
About  the  middle  of  the  century,  especially  through  the 
researches  of  Frankland,  followed  by  those  of  Couper  and 
Kekule",  the  phenomenon  of  multiple  proportions  was  ex- 
plained by  introducing  the  notion  of  saturation.  An 
element  which  can  combine  with  one  or  more  atoms  of 
the  same  or  of  different  elements  or  definite  chemical 
compounds  was  looked  upon  as  having  a  chemical  affinity 
which  might  be  wholly  or  only  partially  satisfied.  The 
different  compounds  arising  out  of  such  combinations 
would  then  represent  different  degrees  of  saturation  of 
the  first  element;  and  it  was  evident  that  elements  as 
well  as  compounds  could  be  arranged  according  to  the 
degrees  of  saturation  of  which  they  were  capable.  A 
compound  containing  elements  which  possessed  a  greater 
capacity  for  saturation  than  the  combination  afforded  was 
called  unsaturated.  The  term  valency  was  introduced  to  45. 
denote  the  degrees  of  saturation  of  elements  and  com- 
pounds, which  were  therefore  mono-,  di-,  or  poly-valent, 
according  to  the  compounds  existing  in  fixed  simple  or 


448  SCIENTIFIC    THOUGHT. 

fixed  multiple  proportions.  In  a  table  of  the  valencies 
or  saturating  capacities  of  elements  and  compounds,  the 
element  hydrogen  forms  the  unit  and  point  of  reference, 
as  it  does  in  the  scale  of  the  atomic  or  combining  weights, 
and  very  remarkable  relations  and  analogies  have  been 
established  between  the  periodic  law  of  Mendeleeff  and 
the  valency  of  the  different  elements.  Nevertheless  it 
must  be  remarked  that  the  valency  of  an  element  or 
compound  does  not,  according  to  our  present  knowledge, 
show  such  absolute  fixity  as  the  equivalents  or  combining 
weights  do,  or  as  the  .angles  of  crystallisation  of  chemically 
pure  substances  do.1 

The  introduction  of  the  conception  of  valency  has  had 
an  enormous  influence  on  the  development  of  the  science 
of  chemistry,  and  this  in  a  twofold  direction.  Its  prac- 
tical use  was  demonstrated  by  Kekule,  when  he  placed 
the  idea  of  the  tetravalency,  or  fourfold  saturating  capa- 
city, of  carbon  in  the  front  of  his  treatise  of  organic 
chemistry,2  and  by  so  doing  gave  a  great  impetus  to 
organic  research.  One  of  the  first  symbols  used  to  denote 

1  Not  only  are  many  of  the  ele-  ;  "no  characteristic  distinction  has 
ments,  such  as  oxygen  and  phos-  been  found,  either  in  physical  or 
phorus,  classed  differently  by  dif-  chemical  behaviour,  between  the 
ferent  chemists  according  as  their  ordinary  compounds  and  the  mo- 
valency  or  saturating  capacity  is  '  lecular  compounds  ;  and  therefore, 


put  at  a  higher  or  lower  multiple, 
but  compounds  which  are  univer- 
sally considered  to  be  saturated 
compounds,  such  as  neutral  salts 


strictly  speaking,  from  the  pheno- 
mena exhibited,  at  present  no  other 
conclusion  can  be  drawn  except 
that  chemical  compounds  do  un- 


and  water,  form  chemical  combina-  doubtedly   exist   which   cannot   be 

tions  according  to  their  combining  !  included  in  the   structure   scheme 

numbers,    which    are    quite    defi-  :  which  is  based  on  the  doctrine  of 

nite  and  stable  :  such  are  the  hy-  ;  a   constant  valency "  (see  Nernst, 

drated    crystallised    salts    and   the  j  '  Theoretical  Chemistry,'  transl.  by 


double  salts.  These  compounds 
are  called  "molecular  compounds." 
Various  explanations  have  been  at- 
tempted, but  the  fact  remains  that 


Palmer,  London,  1895,  p.  246). 

a  A.  Kekute  (1829-1896),  'Lehr- 
buch  der  organischen  Chemie,'  1st 
ed.,  Erlangen,  1859,  and  later. 


THE    ATOMIC    VIEW    OF   NATURE.  449 

the  valency  of  an  element  was  to  attach  to  it  as  many 
lines  as  it  possessed  capacities  of  saturation.  The  capa- 
cities of  saturation  or  valencies  thus  appeared  very  early 
as  points  of  saturation,  and  the  saturation  itself  as  a 
linkage.  These  geometrical  artifices  or  expressions  were, 
for  a  long  time,  used  merely  as  symbols,  and  to  the 
present  day  many  eminent  chemists  refuse  to  attach  to 
them  any  real  meaning :  formulae  of  this  kind  were  called 
formulae  of  structure,  not  of  constitution.  One  of  the  47. 
most  remarkable  instances  of  the  exact  use  of  linkages  linkage, 
to  explain  the  difference  of  a  series  of  organic  compounds, 
all  closely  connected  with  each  other,  is  the  theory  of  the 
so-called  aromatic  compounds,  derived  from  benzene,  which 
we  owe  to  Kekule".  It  has  stood  the  criticism  of  more 
than  a  quarter  of  a  century,  and  has  led  to  the  most 
wonderful  practical  knowledge  of  a  large  number  of  old 
and  new  compounds. 

It  is  not  astonishing  if,  in  the  face  of  these  remark- 
able strides  which  geometrical  symbols  have  led  to, 
an  attempt  has  been  made  to  form  an  actual  con- 
ception of  the  geometrical  figure  and  grouping  of  the 
atoms  of  which  chemical  molecules  and  compounds  are 
made  up. 

Space  relations  are  the  only  ones  in  which  the  differ- 
ence of  symmetry  and  asymmetry  can  be  at  all  conceived 
by  us ;  and  when  chemical  compounds  were  discovered 
which  show  no  other  difference  than  that  one  of  them 
turns  the  plane  of  polarisation  of  a  ray  of  light  passing 
through  it  to  the  right,  the  other  to  the  left  side,  the 
time  seemed  ripe  to  seek  an  explanation  of  this  in  a 
purely  stereometrical  difference  of  form  or  grouping. 

VOL.  I.  2  F 


450 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


In  1874  two  chemists,  Le  Bel  and  Van't  Hoff,  suggested 
independently  a  picture  of  the  tetravalent  carbon  atom, 
which  would  explain  how  it  could  enter  with  its  four 
points  or  capacities  of  saturation  into  two  compounds 
having  the  same  saturating  substances,  but  arranged  in 
ways  which  were  not  geometrically  superposable,  but  only 
symmetrical,  like  a  right-  and  left-hand  glove,  or  the 
48.  images  in  a  mirror.  The  suggestion  amounts  to  this, 

The  carbon 

tetrahedron,  that  the  carbon  atom  has  the  shape  of  a  tetrahedron, 
the  four  corners  representing  the  four  valencies  or  capa- 
cities of  saturation.1 

The  carbon  tetrahedron  is  the  last  step  which  has  been 
taken  in  the  development  of  the  atomic  view  of  matter 
and  of  nature.  No  book  on  organic  chemistry  can  now 
well  avoid  introducing  this  and  other  similar  ways  of 
representing  chemical  relations.  On  the  further  special- 
isation of  this  conception  will  probably  depend  to  a  large 
extent  the  future  of  our  chemical  theory — i.e.,  of  our  at- 
tempts to  grasp  the  qualitative  nature  of  different  sub- 
stances. It  is  clear  that  we  are  far  on  the  way  to  realising 
Wollaston's  prophecy  of  the  year  1808 — viz.,  "that  the 


1  This  speculation  was  at  first 
looked  upon  with  very  great  doubt. 
Only  few  chemists  of  note  took  it 
up  ;  others,  such  as  Kolbe,  who  led 
a  consistent  opposition  to  the  ideas 
and  developments  of  structural 
chemistry,  treated  it  with  ridicule. 
Van't  Hoff,  ten-  years  after  the 
publication  of  the  first  edition  of 
his  pamphlet,  '  La  Chimie  dans 
1'Espace'  (Rotterdam,  1875)  re- 
viewed the  position  in  his  '  Dix 
Anndes  dans  1'Histoire  d'une  The- 
orie'  (translated  by  Marsh,  Oxford, 
1891),  and,  after  reproducing  the 


two  opposite  reviews,  with  which 
the  original  theory  was  met  by 
Wislicenus  and  Kolbe,  was  able  to 
state  "  that  the  theory  in  question 
now  forms  part  of  elementary 
chemical  teaching,  and  is  to  be 
found  enunciated  in  the  most 
widely  used  text-books"  (transla- 
tion, p.  19).  Further  applica- 
tions of  the  theory,  especially  to 
the  compounds  of  nitrogen,  will  be 
found  in  the  2nd  edition  of  the 
German  translation  '  Die  Lagerung 
der  Atome  im  Raume'  (Braunsch- 
weig, 1894). 


THE   ATOMIC   VIEW   OF   NATURE. 


451 


atomic  theory  could  not  rest  contented  with  a  knowledge 
of  the  relative  weights  of  elementary  atoms,  but  would 
have  to  be  completed  by  a  geometrical  conception  of  the 
arrangement  of  the  elementary  particles  in  all  the  three 
dimensions  of  solid  extension."  * 

But  though  a  further  development  of  the  atomic  view, 
not  only  "  pondere  "  but  also  "  menstira,"  may  be  expected 
in  the  near  future,  the  progress  of  chemistry,  which  has 
benefited  so  much  by  this  view  of  nature,  will  not  de-  49. 

Defects  and 

pend  exclusively  upon  this  line  of  thought,  nor  perhaps  insufficiency 

01  tnG 

to  so  large  an  extent  as  it  has  done  during  the  greater  atomic  view, 
part  of  the  century.  We  have  seen  how  the  atomic 
theory  of  Dalton  rose  to  the  position  of  being  more 
than  a  convenient  symbolism,  and  how  it  became  a 
physical  theory  of  matter  and  of  nature  mainly  by 
the  support  which  it  received  from  a  different  line  of 
reasoning. 

The  development  of  this  line  of  reasoning  led  to  the 
employment  of  the  statistical  method,  a  view  quite 
foreign  to  other  branches  of  physical  science. 

The  kinetic  theory  of  gases  itself  had  been  elaborated 
in  connection  with  still  another  line  of  reasoning,  with 
the  endeavour  to  get  a  clearer  and  more  comprehensive 
view  of  the  nature  of  the  different  forces  which  the 
astronomical  as  well  as  the  atomic  views  had  merely 
accepted  as  given  quantities  without  further  examination. 
We  are  thus  necessarily  led  on  to  trace  the  history  of 


1  See  Wollaston's  memoir,  "  On 
Super-acid  aud  Sub-acid  Salts," 
read  before  the  Royal  Society,  Jan. 
8,  1808  ('  Phil.  Trans.,'  1808,  p.  96, 
&c.),  where  he  even  suggests  the 


examination  of  the  stability  of  ag- 
gregates of  particles  in  different  con- 
figurations, mentioning  the  tetra- 
hedron, since  become  celebrated 
through  Pasteur  aud  Van't  Hoff. 


252  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

these  other  views  of  nature,  which  up  to  the  middle  of 
the  century  had  grown  up  independently. 

The  next  chapter  will  accordingly  deal  with  the 
kinetic  view  of  nature. 

At  the  time  when  the  atomic  theory  was  firmly  estab- 
lished and  defined,  the  great  founders  of  chemical  science 
were  well  aware  that  the  investigation  and  measurement 
of  chemical  forces,  of  what  was  termed  affinity,  was  just 
as  important  a  problem  as  the  fixing  of  the  combining 
weights  and  the  formulse  of  chemical  compounds. 

Accordingly  we  find  men  like  Bergmann,  Berthollet, 
Davy,  Berzelius,  and  Faraday  all  propounding  or  suggest- 
so,  ing  theories  of  chemical  affinity,  some  of  which,  like  the 

Theories  of 

chemical      electro-chemical  theory,  remained  long  in  use.     The  diffi- 

affinity.  * 

eulty,  however,  which  was  experienced  in  defining,  and 
still  more  in  measuring,  chemical  affinity,  and  the  absence 
of  a  general  system  for  the  computation  and  calculation 
of  all  physical  quantities,  retarded  the  progress  of  this 
line  of  research  compared  with  the  study  of  the  weights 
or  proportions  of  mass  which  existed  in  chemical  processes, 
and  which  were  more  easily  ascertained  by  means  of  the 
balance,  and  made  intelligible  by  the  atomic  theory. 

The  tendency  of  chemical  reasoning  during  the  first 
half  of  the  century  lay  therefore  in  the  direction  of  a 
one-sided  development  of  the  knowledge  of  matter,  its 
definite  constituents  and  infinite  compounds,  rather  than 
in  a  study  of  that  equally  important  but  more  subtle 
quantity,  now  called  energy,  which  appears  or  disappears, 
but  is  never  created  or  destroyed  in  physical  or  chemical 
processes. 

A  clear  recognition  of  this  fundamental  doctrine — nay, 


THE    ATOMIC   VIEW   OF   NATURE.  453 

even  a  name  for  the  thing  implied — did  not  exist  before 
the  middle  of  the  century.  How  both  were  gradually  intro- 
duced will  be  shown  in  another  of  the  following  chapters. 

The  atomic  view  or  theory  which  gave  such  good  help 
in  classifying  and  in  studying  the  characteristic  feature 
of  all  chemical  processes — the  fact  that  they  take  place 
according  to  definite  proportions  of  weight — had  also  the 
effect  of  promoting  a  somewhat  one-sided  habit  of  thought 
in  the  domain  of  chemical  science  itself. 

The  search  for  the  elements,  the  fixing  of  their  com- 
bining weights  and  properties,  absorbed  a  great  deal  of 
time,  labour,  and  ability. 

The  practical  demands  of  the  arts  stimulated  the  pre-  51. 
paration  of  metals,  of  acids,  and  of  alkalies,  all  of  which  influen 
possessed  useful  properties  in  their  isolated,  as  distin- 
guished from  their  natural,  condition.  This  gave  a  stimu- 
lus in  practice  to  the  invention  of  processes  of  disintegration, 
and  in  reasoning  to  processes  of  analysis.  The  synthesis  or 
putting  together  was  expected  to  take  place  easily,  if  once 
the  elements  or  constituent  parts  were  got.  In  mineral 
chemistry  and  metallurgy  this  is  indeed  very  frequently 
the  case.  It  was  soon  found  that  it  is  not  so  in  organic 
chemistry,  and  that  when  in  organic  chemistry;  a  synthesis 
is  effected,  the  product  is  frequently  unlike  that  original 
natural  substance  from  the  analysis  or  disintegration  of 
which  the  constituents  or  elements  were  procured. 

It  soon  became  evident  that  synthesis  does  not  mean 
merely  addition.  A  certain  order  had  to  be  observed  in 
the  way  of  putting  together,  and  this  led  to  the  introduc- 
tion of  structural,  further  of  geometrical,  formulae.  Even 
then,  however,  it  was  found  that  if  a  synthesis  succeeded, 


SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 


it  did  not  always  produce  a  natural,  but  frequently  a 

purely  artificial,  compound.     The  practical  effect  of  this 

discovery  has  been  remarkable,  not  to  say  astonishing. 

New   industries   have   been    founded,  and   a   branch   of 

science  has  been  created  called  "  organic  chemistry,"  but 

more   correctly  the   "  chemistry  of  carbon   compounds," 

which  was  undreamt  of  in  the  beginning  of  the  century. 

52.        At  that  time  "  organic  chemistry  "  meant  that  branch  of 

definition  of  the  science  which  dealt  with  the  compounds  which  were 

organic 

chemistry,  found  in  the  structures  of  the  vegetable  and  animal 
kingdoms,  and  which  were  peculiar  to  them.1  This 
meaning  of  the  term  "  organic  chemistry "  has  disap- 
peared ;  but  the  branch  of  science  which  deals  specially 
with  the  substances  contained  in  living  matter  has  not 
disappeared.  Only  the  development  of  chemistry  on  the 
lines  pre-eminently  prescribed  by  the  atomic  view  of 
nature  has  diverted  the  attention  of  many  investigators 
and  philosophers  from  the  original  problems  of  organic 
chemistry — the  study,  the  analysis,  and  the  reproduction 
or  synthesis  of  such  compounds  as  are  immediately  con- 
nected with  living  matter. 

To  the  extent  that  these  problems  which  have  not  lain 


1  The  merit  of  having  upheld  the 
twofold  aspect  of  organic  chem- 
istry and  of  having  urged  the 
necessity  of  two  distinct  ways  of 
analysing  organic  substances,  be- 
longs in  this  century  pre-eminently 
to  Chevreul.  Not  only  are  his 
'  Recherches  sur  les  Corps  gras 
d'Origine  animale,'  carried  on  from 
1813  to  1823,  a  model  work  of 
great  theoretical  and  practical 
value ;  but  he  has  in  various  writ- 
ings, notably  in  his  historical 
memoirs  ('Journal  des  Savants,' 


1852-60),  insisted  011  the  necessity 
of  studying  what  he  terms,  after 
Fourcroy,  "  les  principes  iin- 
mediats,  qui  constituent  les 
vegetaux  et  les  auimaux."  This 
study  is  based  upon  quite  a  different 
method  from  that  usually  called 
"  analyse  elcmentaire. "  Chevreul's 
great  work  has  been  continued  and 
developed  by  M.  Berthelot  in  his 
celebrated  book,  '  Chimie  organique 
fondce  sur  la  Synthese,'  1860,  two 
vols. 


THE  ATOMIC  VIEW  OF  NATURE.       455 

specially  on  the  lines  marked  out  by  the  atomic  view  of 
nature  have,  in  the  course  of  time,  reasserted  themselves, 
the  atomic  view  itself  has  been  regarded  with  less  favour 
by  students  who  have  made  these  problems  their  especial 
study.  In  fact,  one  meets  not  infrequently  with  an  in- 
clination to  disparage  the  atomic  theory,  to  point  out 
that  it  is  merely  a  hypothesis,  and  that  as  such  it 
should  only  assist,  but  not  govern,  scientific  research.1 
In  the  domain  of  specially  chemical  reasoning  we  meet  53. 

...  ,,,  '  -i     -i          IP  -IT         i  Criticisms  of 

with  severe  criticisms  01  the  one-sided  and  formal  develop-  the  atomic 

view. 

ment  to  which  the  atomic  view  has  led,  of  the  playing  with 
symbols  and  of  their  empty  formalism  ;  notably  structural 
chemistry  and  stereo-chemistry  have  not  escaped  severe 
ridicule.2  Whilst  it  is  not  very  evident  how  the  school 
from  which  these  criticisms  proceed  can  in  the  long-run 
escape  those  logical  consequences  which  are  embodied 
in  stereo- chemistry,  other  criticisms  claim  our  attention 

1  See    Berthelot,   '  La    Synthese  de  1'esprit  humain,  naturellement 

chimique,'   7me  dd.,   1891,   p.   167.  porte  a  substituer  &  la  conception 

'  Le   principal    reproche,    que    1'on  directe  des  choses  ...  la  vue  plus 

puisse   adresser   a   la   thdorie    ato-  simple  .   .  .  de  leurs  signes  reprd- 

mique,  cotnme  a  toutes  les  concep-  sentatifs." 

tions  analogues,  c'est  qu'elles  con-  ,       2  The    late     eminent    Professor 


duisent  a  opdrer  sur  ces  rapports 
numeriques  des  eldments  et  non 
sur  les  corps  eux-memes,  en  rap- 
portant  toutes  les  rdactions  a  une 
unite  type,  ndcessairement  imag- 


Hermann  Kolbe  of  Leipsic,  whose 
labours  both  alone  and  jointly  with 
Frankland  have  done  so  much  to 
break  down  the  formalism  of  the 
older  type  theory,  was  especially 


inaire.      Bref    elles    enlevent    aux  conspicuous  by  his  virulent  attacks 

phdnomenes    tout    caractere    rdel,  on  the  representatives  of  'Modern 

et    substituent    a    leur    exposition  Chemistry.'      The    controversy    is 

vdritable  une  suite  de  considdrations  elaborately  and  lucidly  treated  by 

symboliques,  auxquelles  1'eaprit  se  A.    Rau    in     '  Die    Theorien     der 

complait,    parce    qu'il    s'y    exerce  modernen  Chemie '  (Braunschweig, 

avec   plus  de  facilitd   que   sur  les  1877-84,  3   parts),   which  contains 

realites  proprement  dites  .   .   .  les  very  valuable  historical  references, 

symboles  de  la  chimie  prdsentant  I  am  afraid  it  is  greatly  owing  to 

a  cet   dgard  d'dtranges  sdductions  this  party  spirit  that  Kolbe's  own 

par  la  facilitd  algebrique  de  leurs  greatness     is     hardly     sufficiently 
combinaisons  et  par  les  tendances   i  known  in  this  country. 


456  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

because  they  follow  from  distinctly  defined  and  inde- 
pendent lines  .of  reasoning.  The  three  criticisms  can  be 
summed  up  in  three  distinct  arguments,  all  three  de- 
manding our  special  and  exhaustive  study.  These  three 
arguments  may  be  summarised  as  follows : — 

First.  The  atomic  view  is  a  hypothesis  resting  upon  the 
fact  that  substances  combine  in  fixed  and  fixed  multiple 
proportions,  and  upon  the  further  observation  that  bodies 
both  in  the  solid  and  liquid  state  show  different  properties 
in  different  directions  of  space.  But  as  to  the  nature 
of  the  differences  of  the  elements  the  atomic  view  gives  no 
information ;  it  simply  asserts  these  differences,  assumes 
them  as  physical  constants,  and  tries  to  describe  them  by 
number  and  measurement. 

The  atomic  view  is  therefore  at  best  only  a  provisional 
basis,  a  convenient  resting-place,1  similar  to  that  which 
Newton  found  in  physical  astronomy,  and  on  which  has 
been  established  the  astronomical  view  of  nature. 

Second.  The  atomic  view  in  its  present  development 
gives  us  no  insight  into  the  nature  of  those  forces  on  which 
depend  the  formation  or  destruction  of  chemical  com- 
pounds. It  neglects  the  study  of  chemical  affinity.  This 
must  be  conducted  on  different  lines  of  observation  and 
reasoning.2 

1  As  these  and  other  points  re-  Very  suggestive  in  the  first  instance 

ferred  to  here  will  be  taken  up  and  is    Lord    Kelvin's    address   to    the 

fully  treated  in  future  chapters  of  mathematical  and  physical  section 

this   work,   I   abstain  from  giving  of  the  British  Association  in  1884, 

exhaustive  references,  limiting  my-  reprinted  in  the  first  volume  of  his 

self     to     such     writings     as     will  '  Popular  Lectures  and  Addresses,' 

give  the  reader  a  general  idea  of  p.  218,  &c.,  "Steps  towards  a  Kin- 

the  various   attempts   which   have  etic  Theory  of  Matter. " 

been  made  to  go  beyond  or  behind  2  In  respect  of  this  the  Introduc- 

the  Atomic  View  of  Nature  or  to  tion  to  the  first  edition  of  Lothar 

supplement    it    by    other    views.  Meyer's  '  Modern  Theories  in  Chem- 


THE   ATOMIC   VIEW   OP   NATURE.  457 

Third.  The  atomic  view,  as  developed  in  chemical  for- 
mulae, has  unduly  favoured  and  promoted  the  analytical 
tendency  of  research  and  thought,  limiting  synthesis 
to  such  compounds  as  can  be  artificially  prepared, 
but  neglecting  that  kind  of  synthesis  by  which  com- 
pounds are  formed  in  nature,  and  especially  in  living 
organisms.1 

As  representative  of  these  three  lines  of  argument, 
leading  beyond  or  outside  of  the  atomic  view  of  nature, 
I  mention  the  three  names  of  Lord  Kelvin  in  England, 
coupled  with  the  kinetic — specially  the  vortex — theory  of 
matter ;  of  Professor  Ostwald  in  Germany,  coupled  with 
the  modern  doctrines  of  chemical  affinity ;  and  of  M. 
Berthelot  in  France,  as  especially  identified  with  the  de- 
velopment of  modern  synthetical  methods  in  chemistry. 
In  the  next  chapter  I  shall  take  up  the  line  of  thought 
embodied  in  the  first  of  these  developments — the  kinetic 
view  of  nature.  In  order  to  understand  the  history  of 
this  view,  we  shall  have  to  go  back  to  opinions  held 


istry,'  written  in  1862  and  reprint- 
ed in  the  subsequent  editions  and 
also  in  the  English  translation  by 
Bedson  and  Williams  (London,  1888), 


ii.  p.  50,  &c.  Professor  Ostwald  is 
also  the  editor,  since  1857,  of  the 
first  periodical  devoted  to  physical 
chemistry.  To  his  great  work, 


gives  a  very  lucid  summary  of  the  entitled       'Allgemeine      Chemie,' 

historical  developments.     The  pub-  which,    since    its    first    appearance 

lication  of   Meyer's  book,    by   the  |   in    1884,   has   done    so    much   for 

controversies    it    produced,    did    a  "  general "    as    distinguished   from 

great  deal  to  give  "  theoretical "  or  "  systematic  "  chemistry,  and  to  his 

"  physical "  chemistry  a  distinct  and  numerous   suggestive   addresses,    I 

independent      position.      Separate  |   shall   frequently  have   occasion   to 

chairs  and  laboratories  for  physical  i   refer. 

chemistry  have  since  been   inaug-  i        1  See  the  works  of  M.  Berthelot, 

urated,  first  at  Leipsic  and  subse-  quoted   above,  pp.    454,  455 ;  also 


quently  at  other  German  univer- 
sities. See  Ostwald's  article  on 
"  Physikalische  Chemie,"  in  Lexis, 


an  address  by  Prof.  Meldola  before 
the  chemical  section  of  the  British 
Association  in  1895. 


'  Die  deutschen  Univeraitaten,'  vol. 

VOL.  I.  2  G 


458  SCIENTIFIC   THOUGHT. 

already  in  antiquity ;  just  as  I  showed  that  the  astro- 
nomical and  atomic  views  of  nature  grew  out  of  vaguer 
theories  of  older  times,  and  that  they  owe  their  revival 
and  scientific  usefulness  to  the  fact  that  they  have  re- 
ceived in  recent  days  the  precise  treatment  of  exact 
measurement  and  mathematical  reasoning. 


END    OF    THE    FIRST   VOLUME. 


PRINTED  BY   WILLIAM   BLACKWOOD   AXD  SONS. 


PHILOSOPHICAL   WORKS. 


SCOTTISH  PHILOSOPHY.  A  COMPARISON  OP  THE  SCOTTISH 
AND  GERMAN  ANSWERS  TO  HUME.  Balfowr  Philosophical  Lectures, 
University  of  Edinburgh.  By  A.  S.  PRINGLE-PATTISON,  LL.D., 
Professor  of  Logic  and  Metaphysics  in  Edinburgh  University.  Fourth 
Edition.  Crown  8vo,  5s. 

THE  PHILOSOPHICAL  RADICALS,  AND  OTHER  ESSAYS, 
including  Chapters  reprinted  on  the  Philosophy  of  Religion  in  Kant 
and  Hegel.  By  the  SAME  AUTHOR.  Crown  8vo,  6s.  net. 

HEGELIANISM  AND  PERSONALITY.  Balfour  Philosophical 
Lectures.  Second  Series.  By  the  SAME  AUTHOR.  Second  Edition. 
Crown  8vo,  5s. 

MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  COSMOS,  AND  OTHER  ESSAYS. 
By  the  SAME  AUTHOR.  Enlarged  Edition.  Post  8vo,  6s.  net. 

TWO  LECTURES  ON  THEISM.  Delivered  on  the  occasion 
of  the  Sesquicentennial  Celebration  of  Princeton  University.  By  the 
SAME  AUTHOR.  Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

A  STUDY  OF  ETHICAL  PRINCIPLES.  By  JAMES  SETH, 
M.A.,  Professor  of  Moral  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Edinburgh. 
Sixth  Edition.  Revised.  Post  8vo,  7s.  6d. 

THE  ETHICS  OF  JOHN  STUART  MILL.  By  CHARLES 
DOUGLAS,  M.A.,  D.Sc.  Post  8vo,  6s.  net. 

JOHN   STUART  MILL.    A  STUDY  OF  HIS  PHILOSOPHY.    By 

the  SAME  AUTHOR.     Crown  8vo,  4s.  6d.  net. 

SCHOPENHAUER'S  SYSTEM  IN  ITS  PHILOSOPHICAL 
SIGNIFICANCE.  (The  Shaw  Fellowship  Lectures,  1893.)  By 
WILLIAM  CALDWELL,  M.A.,  D.Sc.,  Professor  of  Moral  and  Social 
Philosophy,  Northwestern  University,  U.S.A.;  formerly  Assistant  to 
the  Professor  of  Logic  and  Metaphysics,  Edin.,  and  Examiner  in 
Philosophy  in  the  University  of  St  Andrews.  Demy  8vo,  10s.  6d.  net. 

THE  ETHICS  OF  NATURALISM.  Being  the  Shaw  Fellowship 
Lectures,  1884.  By  W.  R.  SORLEY,  LL.D.,  Fellow  of  Trinity  Col- 
lege, Cambridge,  Knightsbridge  Professor  of  Ethics,  University  of 
Cambridge.  Crown  8vo,  6s. 

STUDIES  IN  PHILOSOPHICAL  CRITICISM  AND  CON- 
STRUCTION. By  SYDNEY  HERBERT  MELLONE,  M.A.  Lond., 
D.Sc.  Edin.  Post  8vo,  10s.  6d.  net. 

AN  INTRODUCTORY  TEXT-BOOK  OF  LOGIC.  By  the 
SAME  AUTHOR.  Second  Edition,  Revised.  Crown  8vo,  5s. 

ELEMENTS  OF  PSYCHOLOGY.  By  the  SAME  AUTHOR. 
Crown  8vo,  5s. 


PHILOSOPHICAL   WORKS— continued. 

PHILOSOPHY  AS  SCIENTIA  SCIENTLARUM  A  HIS- 
TORY OF  CLASSIFICATIONS  OF  THE  SCIEXCES.  By  ROBERT  FLINT, 
D.D.,  LL.D.,  Corresponding  Member  of  the  Institute  of  France,  Hon. 
Member  of  the  Royal  Society  of  Palermo,  Professor  in  the  University 
of  Edinburgh,  &c.  12s.  6d.  net. 

STUDIES  OX  THEOLOGICAL,  BIBLICAL,  AND  OTHER 
SUBJECTS.  By  the  SAME  AUTHOR.  7s.  6d.  net. 

HISTORICAL  PHILOSOPHY  IN  FRANCE  AND  FRENCH 
BELGIUM  AND  SWITZERLAND.  By  the  SAME  AUTHOR.  8vo. 
21s. 

AGNOSTICISM.    By  the  SAME  AUTHOR.     Demy  8vo,  18s.  net. 

THEISM.  By  the  SAKE  AUTHOR.  Tenth  Edition,  Revised. 
Crown  8vo,  7s.  6d. 

ANTI-THEISTIC  THEORIES.  By  the  SAME  AUTHOR. 
Fifth  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  10s.  6d. 

SERMONS  AND  ADDRESSES.  By  the  SAME  AUTHOR. 
Demy  8vo,  7s.  6d. 

PHILOSOPHY  OF  THEISM.  BEING  THE  SUBSTANCE  OF  THE 
GDFFORD  LECTURES  DELIVERED  BEFORE  THE  UNIVERSITY  OF  EDIN- 
BURGH IN  1894-96.  By  ALEXANDER  CAMPBELL  FRASER, 
LL.D.,  Eon.  D.C.L.  Oxford,  Emeritus  Professor  of  Logic  and  Meta- 
physics in  the  University  of  Edinburgh.  Second  Edition,  amended. 
Post  8vo,  6s.  6d.  net. 

"The  University  of  Edinburgh  was  well  advised  in  appointing  to  its 
Gifford  Lectureship  the  editor  of  Berkeley  and  Locke.  These  lectures,  as 
a  continuous  piece  of  reasoning,  form  a  notable  contribution  to  philo- 
sophical and  religious  thought." — Quarterly  Re-dew. 

BIOGRAPHIA  PHILOSOPHICA.  By  the  SAME  AUTHOR. 
Demy  8vo,  6s.  net. 

THE  DEVELOPMENT  OF  MODERN  PHILOSOPHY. 
WITH  OTHER  LECTURES  AND  ESSAYS.  By  ROBERT  ADAMSON, 
LL.D.,  late  Professor  of  Logic  in  the  University  of  Glasgow.  Edited 
by  Professor  W.  R.  80RLEY,  University  of  Cambridge.  2  vols., 
demy  8vo,  18s.  net. 


WILLIAM    BLACKWOOD  &  SONS,  EDINBURGH  AND  LONDON. 


Messrs   Blackwood   &   Sons 


Publications 


PERIODS   OF   EUROPEAN   LITERATURE:    A  Complete  and 

CONTINUOUS  HISTORY  OF  THB  SUBJECT.    Edited  by  PBOFKSSOK  SAINTS- 
BURY.     In  12  crown  8vo  vols.,  each  5s.  net. 

I.  THE  DARK  AGES.     By  Professor  W.  P.  KBB. 
II.  THE   FLOURISHING   OF   ROMANCE   AND  THE   RISE  OF 
ALLEGORY.    (12TH  ASD  13TH  CENTURIES.)    By  GEORGE  SAINTS- 
BURY,   M.A.,   Hon.  LL.D.,  Aberdeen,  Professor  of  Rhetoric  and 
English  Literature  in  Edinburgh  University. 

III.  THE  FOURTEENTH  CENTURY.     By  F.  J.  SNBLL. 

IV.  THE  TRANSITION  PERIOD.    By  Prof.  G.  GBHGOBY  SMITH. 
V.  THE  EARLIER  RENAISSANCE.    By  THB  EDITOB. 

VL  THE  LATER  RENAISSANCE.     By  DAVID  HANNAY. 
VII.  THE  FIRST  HALF    OF  THE    SEVENTEENTH  CENTURY. 

By  Prof.  H.  J.  C.  GRIERSON. 

VIII.  THE  AUGUSTAN   AGES.    By  OLIVBB  ELTON. 
IX.  THE  MID-EIGHTEENTH  CENTURY.    By  J.  H.  MILLAR. 
X.  THE  ROMANTIC  REVOLT.     By  Prof.  C.  E.  VAUGHAN. 
XI.  THE  ROMANTIC  TRIUMPH.     By  T.  S.  OMOND. 
XII.  THE  LATER  NINETEENTH  CENTURY.    By  THK  EDITOR. 


PHILOSOPHICAL    CLASSICS 

Edited  by  WILLIAM  KNIGHT, 
in  the  University  of  St  Andrews. 

DESCARTES,  ....  Prof.  Mahaffy. 
BUTLER  ....  Rev.  W.  L.  Collins. 
BERKELEY,  .  .  Prof.  Campbell  Fraser. 

FICHTK, Prof.  Adamson. 

KANT Prof.  Wallace. 

HAMILTON, Prof.  Veitch. 

HEOEL,  ....  The  Master  of  Balliol. 
LKIBNIX,  .  .  .  John  Theodore  Men. 


FOR     ENGLISH     READERS. 

LL.D.,  Professor  of  Moral  Philosophy 
Re-issue  in  Shilling  Volumes  net. 

Vico,  Prof.  Flint. 

HOBBKS,      .    .     .    Prof.  Groom  Robertson. 

HUME Prol.  Knight. 

SPINOZA, Principal  Caird. 

BACON  :  Part  I.,  .  .  .  .  .  Prof.  Nichol. 
BACON  :  Part  II.,  ....  Prof.  Nichol. 
LOCKE Proi.  Campbell  Fraser. 


FOREIGN  CLASSICS  FOR  ENGLISH  READERS,    Edited  by 

Mrs  OLIPHANT.    CHEAP  RE-ISSUE,     In  limp  cloth,  fcap.  8vo,  price  Is. 
each  net. 

DANTE,  by  the  Editor.  —  VOLTAIRE, 
by  General  Sir  E.  B.  Hamley,  K.C.B. 
—  PASCAL,  by  Principal  Tulloch.  —  PE- 
TRARCH, by  Henry  Reeve,  C.B. — GOETHE, 
by  A.  Hayward,  Q.C.— MOLIERE,  by  the 
Editor  and  F.  Tarver,  M.A. — MONTAIGNE, 
by  Rev.  W.  L.  Collins.— RABELAIS,  by  Sir 
Walter  Besant.  —  CALDERON,  by  E.  J. 
Hasell.— SAINT  SIMON,  by  C.  W.  Collins. 


CERVANTES,  by  the  Editor.  —  CORNEILLE 
AND  RACINE,  by  Henry  M.  Trollope.— 
MADAME  DE  SEVIQNE,  by  Miss  Thackeray. 

—  LA    FONTAINE,    AND    OTHER    FRENCH 
FABULISTS,    by    Rev.  W.    Lucas   Collins, 
M.A.  —  SCHILLER,  by  James   Sime,   M.A. 

—  TASSO,   by   E.    J.    Hasell.  —  ROUSSEAU, 
by    Henry    Grey    Graham.  —  ALFRED    DE 
MUSSET,  by  C.  F.  Ollphant. 


ANCIENT  CLASSICS  FOR   ENGLISH  READERS.    Edited  by 

the  Rsv.  W.  LUCAS  COLLINS,  M.A.     CHKAP  RS-IBSUE.     In  limp  cloth, 
fcap.  8vo,  price  Is.  each  net. 


Contentt  of  the  Striei.— HOMER  :  ILIAD, 
by  the  Editor. — HOMER  :  ODYSSEY,  by  the 
Editor.— HERODOTUS,  by  G.  C.  Swayne.— 
CASAR,  by  Anthony  Trollope. — VIROIL,  by 
the  Editor.  —  HORACE,  by  Sir  Theodore 
Martin. — JRSCHYLUS,  by  Bishop  Copies  ton. 
— XENOPHON,  by  Sir  Alex.  Grant. — CICERO, 
by  the  Editor.— SOPHOCLES,  by  C.  W.  Col- 
lins.—PLINY,  by  Rev.  A.  Church  and  W.  J. 
Brodribb.— EURIPIDES,  by  W.  B.  Donne. — 
JUVENAL,  by  E.  Walford.  —  ARISTOPHANES, 
by  the  Editor.— HESIOD  AND  THEOONIB,  by 


J.  Davies.— PLAUTUS  AND  TERENCE,  by  the 
Editor.  —  TACITUS,  by  W.  B.  Donne.— 
LUCIAN,  by  the  Editor.— PLATO,  by  C.  W. 
Collins.  —  GREEK  ANTHOLOGY,  by  Lord 
Neaves. — LIVY,  by  the  Editor.— OVID,  by 
Rev.  A.  Church.  —  CATULLUS,  TIBULLUB, 
AND  PROPERTIUS,  by  J.  Da  vies.— DEMOS- 
THENES, by  W.  J.  Brodribb.— ARISTOTLE, 
by  Sir  Alex.  Grant. — THUCTDIDES,  by  the 
Editor.— LUCRETIUS,  by  W.  H.  Mallock.— 
PINDAR,  by  Rev.  F.  D.  Morice. 


CATALOGUE 

OF 

MESSES   BLACKWOOD    A    SONS' 
PUBLICATIONS 


ACTA  SANCTORUM  HIBERNLfi  ;  Ex  Codice  Salmanticensi. 

Nnnc  primum  integre  edit*  opera  CAROLI  OK  SMEDX  et  JOSEPHI  DC  BACKER,  e 
Soc.  Jean,  Hagiographorum  Bollandianorum ;  Auctore  et  Snmptua  Largiente 
JOANNE  PATRICIO  MARCHIONE  BOTHAE.  In  One  handsome  4to  Volume,  bound  in 
half  roxtrarghe,  £2,  2s. ;  in  paper  cover,  81s.  6d. 

ADAMSON. 

The  Development  of  Modern  Philosophy.  With  other  Lec- 
tures and  Essays.  By  ROBERT  ADAMSON,  LL.D.,  late  Professor  of  Logic  in 
the  University  of  Glasgow.  Edited  by  Professor  W.  R.  SORLEY,  University  of 
Cambridge.  In  2  vols.  demy  8vo,  18s.  net. 

The  Development  of  Greek  Philosophy.    Edited  by  Professor 

SORLEY  and  R.  P.  HARDIE,  M.A.    Demy  8vo,  10s.  6d.  net. 

AIKMAN. 

Manures  and  the  Principles  of  Manuring.    By  C.  M.  AIKMAN, 

D.Sc.,  F.R.8.B.,  &c.,  formerly  Professor  of  Chemistry,  Glasgow  Veterinary 
College,  and  Examiner  in  Chemistry,  University  of  Glasgow,  ftc.  Second 
Impression.  Crown  8vo,  6s.  6d. 

Farmyard  Manure  :  Its  Nature,  Composition,  and  Treatment. 

Crown  8vo,  Is.  6d. 

ALISON. 

History  of  Europe.    By  Sir  ARCHIBALD  ALISON,  Bart.,  D.C.L. 
1.  From  the  Commencement  of  the  French  Revolution  to 

the  Battle  of  Waterloo. 

LIBRARY  EDITION,  14  vols.,  with  Portraits.    Demy  SVG,  £10,  10s. 
ANOTHER  EDITION,  in  20  vols.  crown  Svo,  £8. 
PEOPLE'S  EDITION.  13  vols.  crown  Svo,  £2,  11s. 

S.  Continuation  to  the  Accession  of  Louis  Napoleon. 

LIBRARY  EDITION,  8  vols.  Svo,  £8,  7s.  6d. 
PEOPLE'S  EDITION,  8  vols.  crown  Svo  34s. 

Epitome  of  Alison's   History   of  Europe.      Thirtieth   Thou- 
sand, 7s.  6d. 
Atlas  to  Alison's  History  of  Europe.     By  A.  Keith  Johnston. 

LIBRARY  EDITION,  demy  4to,  £3,  Ss. 
PEOPLE'S  EDITION,  31s.  (3d. 

ANCIENT  CLASSICS  FOR   ENGLISH   READERS.     Edited 

by  Rev.  W.  LUCAS  COLLINS,  M.A.     Price  Is.  each  net     for  Utt  o/  Volt,  tee  p.  2. 

ARMYTAGE.    Maids  of  Honour.    By  A.  J.  GREEN-ARMYTAGE. 

Crown  Svo,  10s.  6d.  net. 

ATKINSON.      Local    Government    in    Scotland.       By  MABEL 

ATKINSON,  M.A.    In  1  vol.  demy  Svo,  5s.  net. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


AYTOUH. 

Lays  of  the  Scottish  Cavaliers,  and  other  Poems.     By  W. 

EDMOXTSTOCJ.-*  Arrorx,  D.C.L.,  Professor  of  Rhetoric  and  Belles -Lettres  in  tht 
University  of  Edinburgh,    New  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo,  Ss.  M. 
CHJLAP  EDITIOS.    li.    Cloth,  li.  3d. 

An  Illustrated  Edition  of  the  Lays  of  the  Scottish  Cavaliers 

From  design*  by  Sir  KOSL  PATCH.    Cheaper  Edition.    Small  4to,  10s.  6d. 

BADEN  -  POWELL.      Ballooning  as  a  Sport.      By  Major  B. 

BADKX-POWXLL.    With  EUnstrations.    Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d.  net. 

BARBOUR    Thoughts  from  the  Writings  of  R  W.  BARBOTJK. 

Pott  8vo,  limp  leather,  2s.  6d.  net 

"BARFLEUR"  Naval  PoHcy.    A  Plea  for  the  Study  of  War. 

By  "  Barfleur."    Demy  8vo,  2s.  6d-  net 

BARRLNGTON. 

The  King's  FooL    By  MICHAEL  BARRESTGTOX.    Crown  8vo,  6s, 
The    Reminiscences    of    Sir    Barrington    Beaumont,    Bart. 

A  Novel.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

BARTLETT. 

The    Siege    and    Capitulation    of    Port    Arthur.      Second 

Impression.    By  E.  ASHXEAD  BABTLKTT.    Demy  Svo,  21s.  net 

Richard  Langhorne  :  The  Story  of  a  Socialist.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 
BELLESHEIM.     History  of  the  Catholic  Church  of  Scotland. 

Prom  the  Introduction  of  Christianity  to  the  Present  Day.  By  ALFHOKS  BSL- 
T.Bnrgnt,  D.D.,  Canon  oi  Aii-la-Chapelle.  Translated,  with  Notes  and  Additions, 
by  D.  OSWALD  HUKTKB  BLAIR,  O.S.B.,  Monk  of  Fort  Augustas  Cheap  Edition. 
Complete  in  4  vols.  demy  8vo,  with  Map* .  Price  Sla.  net. 

BLACK      The    Scots    Churches   in    England.      By    KESTTETH 

MACLEOD  BLACK.      Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

BLACKBURN. 

A  Burgher  Quixote.    By  DOUGLAS   BLACKBUBJ*,  Author  of 

'  Prinsloo  of  Prinsloosdorp.'  Second  Impression.  With  Frontispiece.  Crown 
Svo,  6s. 

Richard  Hartley :  Prospector.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

BLACKWOOD. 

Annals  of  a  Publishing  House.     William  Blackwood  and  his 

Sons ;  Their  Magmring  md  Friends.  By  Mrs  OLIPHAXT.  With  Four  Portraits. 
TUrd  Edition.  Demy  Svo.  Vols.  I.  and  II.  £2.  2a. 

Annals  of  a  Publishing  House.     Vol.  in.     John  Blackwood. 

By  his  Daughter  Mrs  BLACKWOOD  PORTKK.  With  2  Portraits  and  View  of  Strath- 
tyrum.  Demy  Svo,  21s. 

Black-wood's   Magazine,   from    Commencement    in    1817    tc 

June  1908.    No*.  1  to  1112,  forming  1S3  Volumes. 

Tales  from  Blackwood.   First  Series.    Price  One  Shilling  each 

in  Paper  Cover.    Sold  separately  at  all  Railway  Bookstalls. 

They  may  also  be  had  bound  in  12  vols.,  cloth,  18s.    Half  calf,  richly  gilt,  SOa 

Or  the  15  vola.  in  «.  rnrhrrahA    91a.      W«lf  red  mnroero.  We. 

Tales  from  Blackwood.     Second  Series.     Complete  in  Twenty- 

four  Shilling  Parts.  Handsomely  bound  in  12  vol* ,  cloth,  30s.  in  leather  back, 
roxburghe  style,  87s.  6d.  Half  calf,  gilt,  52s.  6d  Half  moroKO,  55s. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


BLACKWOOD. 

Tales  from  Blackwood.     Third  Series.    Complete  in  Twelve 

Shilling  Parts.    Handsomely  bound  in  6  Tola.,  cloth,  15s.;  and  in  12  vols.    cloth, 
18s.    The  6  vols.  in  roxbnrghe  Sis.     Half  calf,  25s.     Half  morocco,  28s. 

Travel,  Adventure,  and  Sport.    From  '  Blackwood's  Magazine. 

Uniform  with  'Tales  from  Blackwood.1    In  Twelve  Parts,  sach  price  Is.    Hand- 
somely bound  In  6  vols..  cloth,  15s.     And  in  half  calf,  25s. 

New  Educational  Series.     See  separate  Educational  Catalogue. 
New  Uniform  Series  of  Novels  (Copyright). 

Crown  8vo,  cloth.     Price  3s.  6d.  each.    Now  ready  :— 

WENDERHOLMB.    By  P.  Q.  Hainorton.  ]  MARMORNE.    By  P.  O.  Hamerton. 

THE  STORY  OF  MARQREDEL. 

Meldrnm. 

Hiss  MARJORIBANKB.     By  Mrs  Oliphant. 
THE  PERPETUAL  OX/RATE,  and  THE  RECTOR 

By  the  Same. 
SALEM  CHAPEL,  and  THE  DOCTOR'S  FAMILY. 

By  the  Same. 

A  SENSITIVE  PLANT.     By  E.  D.  Gerard. 
LADY  LEE'S  WIDOWHOOD.     By  Genera:  Sir 

B.  B.  Hamley. 


KATIE  STEWART,  and  other  Stories.    By  Mrs 

Oliph&ut. 

VALENTINE  AND  ais  BROTHER.    By  the  Same. 
SONS  AND  DAUGHTERS.     By  the  Same. 


By  D.  Storrar  |  BEATA.    By  B.  D.  Gerard. 

BI.GGAR  MY  NEIGHBOUR.    By  the  Same. 
THE  WATERS  or  HERCULES.    By  the  Same. 
PAIR  TO  SEE.    By  L.  W.  M.  Lockhart. 
MINE  is  THINE.    By  the  Same. 
DOUBLES  AND  QUITS.    By  the  Same. 
ALTIORA  PKTO.    By  Laurence  Oliphant. 
PICCADILLY.    By  the  Same.    With  Illustra- 
tions. 
LADY  BABY.    By  D.  Gerard. 


THE  BLACKSMITH  OF  VOE.  By  Paul  Gushing. 
MY  TRIVIAL  LIFE  AND  MISFORTUNE.     By  A 

Plain  Woman. 
POOR  NELLIE.     By  the  Sam*. 


Standard   Novels.      Uniform    in    size    and    binding. 

complete  in  one  Volume. 


Each 


FLORIN  SERIES,  Illustrated  Boards.     Bound  in  Cloth,  2s.  6d. 


TOM  CRINGLE'S  Loo.    By  Michael  Scott. 
THE  CRUISE  OF  THE  MIDGE.    By  the  Same. 
OYRIL  THORNTON.    By  Captain  Hamilton. 
ANNALS  OF  THE  P  IRISH.     By  John  Gait. 
THE  PROVOST,  &c     By  the  Same. 
3iR  ANDREW  WYLIE.     By  the  Same 
THE  ENTAIL.    By  the  Same. 
Miss  MOLLY.    By  Beatrice  May  Butt. 
REGINALD  DALTON.     By  J.  G.  Lockhart. 


PEN  OWEN.     By  Dean  Hook. 

ADAM  BLAIR.    By  J.  G.  Lockhart. 

LADY  LEE'S  WIDOWHOOD.   By  General  Sir  B. 

B.  Hamley. 

SALEM  CHAPEL.     By  Mrs  Oliphant. 
THE  PERPETUAL  CURATE.    By  the  Same. 
Miss  MARJORIBANKS.     By  the  Same. 
JOHN  ;  A  Love  Story.    By  the  Same. 


SHILLING  SERIES,  Illustrated  Cover.    Bound  in  Cloth,  Is.  M. 

THE  RECTOR,  and  THE  DOCTOR'S  FAMILY.  SIR   FRIMLE  PUMPKIN,  NIGHTS  AT  MESS, 

By  Mrs  Oliphant.  &c. 

THE   LIFE  OF  MANSIE  WAUCH.     By  D.  M.  THE  SUBALTERN. 

Moir  LIFE  IN  THE  FAR  WEST.    By  G.  F.  Ruxton. 

PENINSULAR   SCENES   AND  SKETCHES.      By  VALERIUS  :    A    Roman    Story.      By  J.   G. 

F.  Hardman.  Lockhart. 


BON    GAULTIER'S   BOOR   OF   BALLADS.     A  new  Edition, 

with  Autobiographical  Introduction  by  Sir  THEODORE  MARTIN,  K.C.B.    With 
Illustrations  by  Doyle,  Leech,  and  Crowquill.    Small  quarto,  5s.  net 

BOWHILL.    Questions  and  Answers  in  the  Theory  and  Practice 

of  Military  Topography.     By  Major  J.  H.  BOWHILL.     Crown  8vo,  4§.  6d.  net. 
Portfolio  containing  34  working  plans  and  diagrams,  3s.  6d.  net. 

BREADALBANE.    The  High  Tops  of  Black  Mount.    By  THE 

MARCHIONESS    OF    BREADALBANE.      Second    Impression.      With   Illustrations 
from  Photographs  by  Olive  Mackenzie.    Short  demy,  6s.  net. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


BRUCE.    In  the  Footsteps  of  Marco  Polo.    Being  the  Account  of 

a  Journey  Overland  from  Simla  to  Pekln.  By  Major  CLARENCE  DALRYMPLK 
BRUCE.  With  Illustrations.  •  Demy  8vo,  21s.  net. 

BUCHAN. 

The  Watcher  by  the  Threshold,  and  other  Tales.    By  JOHN 

BUCHAK.    Second  Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

A  Lodge  in  the  Wilderness.     Second  Impression.     Short  demy 

8  TO,  6s. 

BURBIDGE. 

Domestic  Floriculture,  Window  Gardening,  and  Floral  Decora- 
tions. Being  Practical  Directions  for  the  Propagation,  Culture,  and  Arrangement 
of  Plants  and  Flowers  as  Domestic  Ornaments.  By  F.  W.  BURBIDGK.  Second 
Edition.  Crown  Svo,  with  numerous  Illustrations,  7a.  6d. 

BURTON, 

The  History  of  Scotland  :   From  Agricola's  Invasion  to  the 

Extinction  of  the  last  Jacobite  Insurrection.  By  JOHN  HILL  BURTON,  D.C.L., 
Historiographer-  Royal  for  Scotland  Cheaper  Edition.  In  8  vols.  Crown  8vo, 
2s.  6d.  net  each.  Being  issued  in  Monthly  volumes. 

The  Book -Hunter.     A  New  Edition,  with  specially  designed 

Title-page  and  Cover  by  JOSEPH  BROWN.  Printed  on  antique  laid  paper.  Post 
Svo,  3s.  6d. 

The  Scot  Abroad.     Uniform  with 'The  Book -Hunter.'    Post 

8vo,  3s.  6d. 

BUTE. 

The    Roman    Breviary :    Reformed  by   Order  of    the  Holy 

Oecumenical  Council  of  Trent ;  Published  by  Order  of  Pope  St  Pius  V. ;  and 
Revised  by  Clement  VIII.  and  Urban  VIII. ;  together  with  the  Offices  since 
granted.  Translated  out  of  Latin  into  English  by  JOHN,  MARQUESS  OF  BUTE, 
K.T.  New  Edition,  Revised  and  Enlarged.  In  4  vols.  crown  Svo,  and  in  1  vol. 
crown  4to.  [In  the  press. 

The  Altus  of  St  Columba.   With  a  Prose  Paraphrase  and  Notes 

By  JOHN,  MARQUESS  OF  BUTH,  K.T.    In  paper  cover,  2s.  6d. 

Sermones,     Fratris     Adae,     Ordinis     Prsemonstratensis,     &c. 

Twenty-eight  Discourses  of  Adam  Scotus  of  Whithorn,  hitherto  unpublished ; 
to  which  is  added  a  Collection  of  Notes  by  the  same,  illustrative  of  the  rule  of 
St  Augustine.  Edited,  at  the  desire  of  the  lateJlARQUESs  OF  BUTE,  K.T.,  LL.D., 
&c.,  by  WALTER  DE  GRAY  BIRCH,  LL.D.,  F.S.A.,  of  the  British  Museum,  &c. 
Royal  Svo,  25s.  net. 

Catalogue  of  a  Collection  of  Original  MSS.  formerly  belonging 

to  the  Holy  Office  of  the  Inquisition  in  the  Canary  Islands.  Prepared  under  the 
direction  of  the  late  MARQUESS  OF  BUTE,  K.T.,  LL.D.,  by  WALTER  DE  GRAY 
BIRCH,  LL.D.,  F.S.A.  2  vols.  royal  Svo,  £3,  3s.  net. 

BUTE,    MACPHAIL,    AND    LONSDALE.     The  Arms  of  the 

Royal  and  Parliamentary  Burghs  ol  Scotland.  By  JOHN,  MARQUESS  OF  BUTE, 
K.T.,  J.  R.  N.  MACPHAIL,  and  H.  W.  LONSDALE.  With  131  Engravings  on 
wood,  and  11  other  Illustrations.  Crown  4to.  £2,  2s.  net. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


BUTE,  STEVENSON,  AND  LONSDALE.     The  Arms  of  the 

Baronial  and  Police  Burghs  of  Scotland.  By  JOHN,  MARQUESS  OF  BUTE,  K.T., 
J.  H.  STEVENSON,  and  H.  W.  LONSDALB.  With  numerous  Illustrations.  Crown 
4to,  £2,  2s.  net. 


CAIKD.     Sermons.     By  JOHN    CAIKD,  D.D.,  Principal  of  the 

University  of  Glasgow.    Seventeenth  Thousand.    Fcap.  8vo,  5s. 

CALDWELL.  Schopenhauer's  System  in  its  Philosophical  Sig- 
nificance (the  Shaw  Fellowship  Lectures,  1893).  By  Professor  WILLIAM  CALD- 
WELL, D.Sc.,  M'Qill  University,  Montreal.  Demy  8vo,  10s.  6d.  net. 

CALL  WELL. 

The  Effect  of  Maritime  Command  on  Land  Campaigns  since 

Waterloo.    By  Col.  C.  B.  CALLWBLL,  C.B.    With  Plans.   Post  8vo,  6s.  net. 

Tactics  of  To-day.  Sixth  Impression.   Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d.  net. 

Military  Operations  and  Maritime  Preponderance :  Their  Re- 
lations and  Interdependence.    Demy  8vo,  15s.  net. 

The  Tactics  of  Home  Defence.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d.  net. 

CAKEY. 

Monsieur  Martin :  A  Romance  of  the  Great  Northern  War. 

By  WYMGNI>  CAREY.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

"N9-  101."    Third  Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s.    Cheap  Edi- 
tion, royal  8vo,  paper  covers,  6d. 

CARLYLE.      A  History  of  Mediaeval  Political  Theory  in  the 

West.  By  R.  W.  CARLYLE,  C.I.B.,  Balliol  College,  Oxford ;  and  A.  J.  CARLYLE, 
M.A.,  Chaplain  and  Lecturer  (late  Fellow)  of  University  College,  Oxford.  In  3 
vols.  demy  8vo.  Vol.  I. — A  History  of  Political  Theory  from  the  Roman  Lawyers 
of  the  Second  Century  to  the  Political  Writers  of  the  Ninth.  By  A.  J.  CARLYLE. 
15s.  net. 

CHESNEY.    The  Dilemma.    By  General  Sir  GEOKGE  CHESNEY, 

K.C.B.    A  New  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  2s. 

CHRISTIE.    The  Influence  of  Letters  on  the  Scottish  Reforma- 
tion.   By  Rev.  GEORGE  CHRISTIE,  B.D.    Crown  8vo,  6s.  net. 

CHURCH  SERVICE  SOCIETY. 

A  Book  of  Common  Order :  being  Forma  of  Worship  issued 

by  the  Church  Service  Society.  Seventh  Edition,  carefully  revised.  In  1  vol. 
crown  8vo,  cloth,  3s.  6d. ;  French  morocco,  6s.  Also  In  8  vols.  crown  8vo, 
cloth,  4s. ;  French  morocco,  6s.  6d. 

Daily  Offices  for  Morning  and  Evening  Prayer  throughout 

the  Week.    Crown  8vo,  Ss.  6d. 

Order  of  Divine  Service  for  Children.    Issued  by  the  Church 

Service'Society.     With  Scottish  Hymnal.    Cloth,  3d. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


CLIFFORD. 

Sally :  A  Study ;  and  other  Tales  of  the  Outskirts.    By  HUGH 

CLIFFORD,  C.M.G.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Bush  -  Whacking,  and  other  Sketches.     Second  Impression. 

Grown  Svo,  6s. 

CLODD.    Thomas  Henry  Huxley.    "Modern  English  Writers." 

By  EDWARD  GLODD.    Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

CLOUSTON. 

The  Lunatic  at  Large.      By  J.  STORER  CLOUSTON.      Ninth 

Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s.    CHKAP  EDITIOK,  royal  Svo,  paper  cover,  6d. 

Count  Bunker :  Being  a  Sequel  to  '  The  Lunatic  at  Large.' 

Third  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s.    CHEAP  EDITION,  royal  Svo,  papers  covers,  6d. 

The  Adventures  of  M.  D'Haricot.     Third  Impression.     Crown 

Svo,  6s.    CHKAP  EDITION,  royal  Svo,  paper  cover,  6d. 

Our  Lady's  Inn.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 
Garmiscath.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

CONRAD. 

Lord  Jim.     A  Tale.     By  JOSEPH  CONB.AD,  Author  of  'The 

Nigger  of  the  Narcissus,'  'An  Outcast  of  the  Islands,'  'Tales  of  Unrest,'  &c. 
Second  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Youth :  A  Narrative ;  and  Two  other  Stories.     Second  Im- 
pression.   Crown  Svo,  6s. 

COOPER.     Liturgy  of  1637,  commonly  called  Laud's  Liturgy. 

Edited  by  the  Rev.  Professor  COOPER,  D.D.,  Glasgow.    Crown  Svo,  7s.  6d.  net. 

CORNFORD,     R  L.  Stevenson.     "Modern  English  Writers." 

By  L.  COPE  CORXFORD.    Second  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

COUNTY  HISTORIES  OF  SCOTLAND.     In  demy  Svo  vol- 
umes of  about  350  pp.  each.    With  Maps.    Price  7s.  6d.  net. 

Fife  and  Kinross.     By  AENEAS  J.  G.  MACKAY,  LL.D.,  Sheriff 

of  these  Counties. 

Dumfries  and  Galloway.    By  Sir  HEBBEBT  MAXWELL,  Bart., 

M.P.    Second  Edition. 

Moray  and    Nairn.     By  CHARLES  RAMPINI,  LL.D.,  Sheriff 

of  Dumfries  and  Galloway. 

Inverness.    By  J.  CAMEBON  LEES,  D.D. 

Roxburgh,  Selkirk,  and  Peebles.    By  Sir  GEORGE  DOUGLAS, 

Bart 

Aberdeen  and  Banff.    By  WILLIAM  WATT,  Editor  of  Aberdeen 

'Daily  Free  Press.' 

Perth  and  Clackmannan.    By  JOHN  CHISHOLM,  M.A.,  Advocate. 

[In  flu  press. 

CRAJK.    A  Century  of  Scottish  History.    From  the  Days  before 

the  '45  to  those  within  living  Memory.    By  Sir  HKSRT  CRAIK,  K.C.B.,  M.A. 
(Oion.),  Hon.  LL.D.  (Glasgow).    2  vols.  demy  Svo,  80s.  net. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


CRAWFORD.    Saracinesca.    By  F.  MARION  CRAWFORD,  Author 

at  <  Mr  Isaacs,'  Ac.,  &c.    Grown  8vo,  3s.  6d.    Also  at  6d. 

CROSS. 

Impressions  of  Dante  and  of  the  New  World.    By  J.  W.  CROSS. 

Post  Svo,  6s. 

The  Rake's  Progress  in  Finance.    Crown  Svo,  2s.  net. 

CUMMING. 

Memories.    By  C.  F.  GORDON  GUMMING.     Demy  Svo.    Illus- 
trated, 20s  net. 

At  Home  in  Fiji.    Post  Svo.    Illustrated.    Cheap  Edition,  6s. 
A  Lady's  Cruise  in  a  French  Man-of-War.     Post  Svo.    Illus- 
trated.   Cheap  Edition.    6s. 

Fire- Fountains.     2  vols.  post  Svo.    Illustrated,  25s. 
Granite  Crags.    Post  Svo.    Illustrated.    Cheap  Edition.    6s. 
Wanderings  in  China.     Small  post  Svo.    Cheap  Edition.    6s. 

DAVIS.    "When  Half-Gods  Go."    By  JESSIE  AINSWORTH  DAVIS. 

Second  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

DE   HAVEN.     The  Scarlet  Cloak.      By  AUDREY  DE  HAVEN. 

Crown  Svo,  6s. 

DESCARTES.      The   Method,   Meditations,   and   Principles   of 

Philosophy  of  Descartes.  Translated  from  the  original  French  and  Latin. 
With  a  new  Introductory  Essay,  Historical  and  Critical,  on  the  Caitesian  Phil- 
osophy. By  Professor  VEITCH,  LL.D.  Fourteenth  Edition.  Crown  Svo,  6s.  6d. 

DIVER. 

Captain  Desmond,  V.C.    By  MAUD  DIVER.    Sixth  Impression. 

Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Great  Amulet.    Second  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 
DODDS  AND  MACPHERSON.    The  Licensing  Acts  (Scotland) 

Consolidation  and  Amendment  Act,  1903.  Annotated  by  Mr  J.  M.  DODDS,  C.B., 
of  the  Scottish  Office ;  Joint-Editor  of  the  '  Parish  Council  Guide  for  Scotland,' 
and  Mr  EWAN  MACPHERSON,  Advocate,  Legal  Secretary  to  the  Lord  Advocate. 
In  1  vol.  crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

DOUGLAS. 

The  Ethics  of  John  Stuart  Mill.      By  CHARLES    DOUGLAS, 

M.A.,  D.Sc.,  late  Lecturer  in  Moral  Philosophy,  and  Assistant  to  the  Pro- 
fessor of  Moral  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Edinburgh.  Post  Svo,  6s.  net. 

John  Stuart  Mill :  A  Study  of  his  Philosophy.    Crown  Svo, 

4s.  fid.  net. 

ECCOTT. 

Fortune's  Castaway.    By  W.  J.  ECCOTT.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

His  Indolence  of  Arras.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
Hearth  of  Hutton.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
The  Red  Neighbour.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 


io  Wilham  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


ELIOT. 

The  New  Popular  Edition  of    George  Eliot's  Works,   with 

Photogravure  Frontispiece  to  each  Volume,  from  Drawings  by  William 
Hatherell,  R.I.,  Edgar  Bundy,  R.I.,  Byam  Shaw,  R.I.,  A.  A.  Van  Anrooy, 
Maurice  Greiffenhagen,  Claude  A.  Shepperson,  R.I.,  B.  J.  Sullivan,  and  Max 
Cowper.  Bach  Work  complete  in  One  Volume.  Handsomely  bound,  gilt  top. 
3s.  6d.  net.  Ten  Volumes  in  all. 

SILAS   MARKER  ;    BROTHER   JACOB  ;    THE 


ADAM  BEDE. 

SCENES  OF  CLERICAL  LIFE. 
THE  MILL  ON  THE  FLOSS. 
FELIX  HOLT,  THE  RADICAL. 

MlDDLEMARCH. 


LIFTED  VEIL. 
ROMOLA. 

DANIEL  DERONDA. 
THE  SPANISH  GYPSY  ;  JUBAL. 


ESSAYS  ;  THEOPHRASTUS  SUCH. 

George  Eliot's  Life.     With  Portrait  and  other  Illustrations. 

New  Edition,  In  one  volume.    Crown  8vo,  7s.  6d. 

Life  and  Works  of  George  Eliot  (Warwick  Edition).  14  vol- 
umes, cloth,  limp,  gilt  top,  2s.  net  per  volume  ;  leather,  limp,  gilt  top,  2s.  6d.  net 
per  volume ;  leather  gilt  top,  with  book-marker.  3s.  net  per  volume. 


ADAM  BEDE.    826  pp. 

THE  MILL,  ON  THE  FLOSS.    828  pp. 

FELIX  HOLT,  THE  RADICAL.     718  pp. 

ROMOLA.     900  pp. 

SCENES  OF  CLERICAL  LIFE.    624  pp. 

SILAS   MARNER  ;    BROTHER   JACOB  ;    THE 


MIDDLEMARCH.     2  vols.     664  and  630  pp. 
DANIEL    DERONDA.      2    vols.      616    and 

636  pp. 

THE  SPANISH  GYPSY;  JUBAL 
ESSAYS  ;   THEOPHRASTUS  SUCH. 
LIFB.     2  vols.,  626  and  580  pp. 


LIFTED  VEIL.    560  pp. 

Works  of   George   Eliot  (Standard   Edition).      21    volumes, 

crown  8vo.      In  buckram  cloth,  gilt  top,  2s.  6d.  per  vol.  J   or  In  roxburghe 
binding,  3s.  6d.  per  vol. 

ADAM  BEDE.    2  vols. — THI  MILL  OK  THE  FLOSS.    S  vols. — FSLJX  HOLT,  THE 
RADICAL.    2  vols. — ROMOLA.    2  vols. — SCENES  OF  CLERICAL  LIFE.     2  vols.— 

MlDDLKMARCH.      3  VOlS.— DANIEL    DERONDA.       8  VOlS.— SlLAS   MARNER.       1  VOl. 

— JUBAL.    1  vol.— TH«  SPANISH  GYPSY.    1  vol.— ESSAYS.    1  vol.— THEOPHRAS- 
TUS  SUCH.    1  vol. 

Life  and   Works    of   George    Eliot    (Cabinet    Edition).      24 

volumes,  crown  8vo,  price  £6.    Also  to  be  had  handsomely  bound  in  half  and  full 
calf.    The  Volumes  are  sold  separately,  bound  in  cloth,  price  5s.  each. 

Novels  by  George  Eliot.    Popular  Copyright  Edition.    In  new 

uniform  binding,  price  3s.  6d.  each. 


ADAM  BEDE. 

THB  MILL  ON  THE  FLOSS. 

SCENES  OF  CLERICAL  LIFE. 

ROMOLA. 


SILAS  MARNER;  THE  LIFTED  VEIL; 

BROTHER  JACOB. 
MIDDLEMARCH. 
DANIEL  DERONDA. 


FELIX  HOLT,  THH  RADICAL. 

Essays.    New  Edition.     Crown  8vo,  5&. 

Impressions  of  Theophrastms  Such.     New  Edition.     Crown 

8vo,  5s. 

The  Spanish  Gypsy.    New  Edition.    Crown  8ro,  6s. 

The    Legend    of   Jubal,   and    other    Poems,    Old    and    New- 

New  Edition.     Crown  8vo,  5s. 

Silas  Marner.     New  Edition,  with  Illustrations  by  Reginald 

Birch.     Crown    8vo,    Is.    6d.   net.      Cheap    Edition,  2s.  6d.     Cheap   Edition, 
royal  8vo,  paper  cover,  price  6d. 

Scenes  of  Clerical  Life.  Cheap  Edition,  3s.  Illustrated  Edi- 
tion, with  20  Illustrations  by  H.  R.  Millar,  crown  8vo,  2s. ;  paper  covers,  Is. 
Cheap  Edition,  royal  8vo,  in  paper  cover,  price  6d. 

Felix  Holt.    Cheap  Edition.    Hoyal  8vo,  in  paper  cover,  6d. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons.  n 


ELIOT. 

Adam  Bede.     Cheap  Edition,  royal  8vo,  in  paper  cover,  price 

6d.  New  Edition,  crown  8vo,  paper  cover,  Is.;  crown  8vo,  with  Illustrations, 
cloth.  2a 

The  Mill  on  the  Floss.     Cheap  Edition,  royal  8vo,  in  paper 

cover,  price  6d.    New  Edition,  paper  covers,  Is. ;  cloth,  2s. 

Wise,  Witty,  and  Tender  Sayings,  in  Prose  and  Verse.    Selected 

from  the  Works  of  GKORGI  ELIOT.    New  Edition.    Fcap.  Svo,  SB.  8d. 

ELLIS. 

Barbara  Winslow,  Rebel.     By  BETH  ELLIS.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Madame,  Will  You  Walk  ?    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Blind  Mouths.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Moon  of  Bath.    Fourth  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

ELTON.  The  Augustan  Ages.  "  Periods-  of  European  Litera- 
ture." By  OLIVER  ELTON,  M.A.,  Professor  of  English  Literature,  University 
College,  Liverpool.  Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

EVERARD.    History  of  the  Royal  and  Ancient  Golf  Club,  St 

Andrews.  By  H.  S.  C.  EVERARD.  With  Eight  Coloured  Portraits,  and  many 
other  Unique  Illustrations.  Crown  4to,  21s.  net. 

FAHIE.     A  History  of  Wireless  Telegraphy.     Including  some 

Bare-wire  Proposals  for  Subaqueous  Telegraphs.  By  J.  J.  FAHIE,  Member  of  the 
Institution  of  Electrical  Engineers,  London,  and  of  the  Societe  Internationale 
des  Electrieiens,  Paris ;  Author  of  '  A  History  of  Electric  Telegraphy  to  the 
Year  1837,'  &c.  With  Illustrations.  Third  Edition,  Revised.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

FERGUSSON.     Scots  Poems.    By  ROBERT  FEKGUSSON.     With 

Photogravure  Portrait.  Pott  Svo,  gilt  top,  bound  in  cloth,  Is.  net;  leather, 
Is.  6d.  net. 

FERRIER.      Philosophical  Remains.    Crown  Svo,  14s. 

FLINT. 

Philosophy  as  Scientia  Scientiarum.  A  History  of  Classifica- 
tions of  the  sciences.  By  ROBERT  FLINT,  D.D.,  LL.D.,  Corresponding  Member 
of  the  Institute  of  France,  Hon.  Member  of  the  Royal  Society  ol  Palermo,  Pro- 
fessor in  thn  University  of  Edinburgh,  &c.  12s.  6d.  net. 

Studies  on  Theological,  Biblical,  and  other  Subjects.   7s.  6d.  net. 
Historical   Philosophy  in  France   and   French   Belgium  and 

Switzerland.    Svo,  21s. 

Theism.     Being  the  Baird  Lecture  for  1876.    Tenth  Edition, 

Revised.    Crown  Svo,  7s.  6d. 

Anti-Theistic  Theories.    Being  the  Baird  Lecture  for  1877. 

Fifth  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  10s.  6d. 

Sermons  and  Addresses.     Demy  Svo,  7s.  6d 
FOREIGN  CLASSICS  FOR  ENGLISH   READERS.     Edited 

by  Mrs  OLIPHANT.     Price  Is.  each  net.    for  Litt  0}  Volumes,  Kt  pagt  8. 

FORREST. 

History  of  the  Indian  Mutiny.     By  G.  W.  FORREST,  C.I.E. 

Ex-Director  of  Records,  Government  of  India.    2  vols.  demy  8yo,  38s.  net. 

Sepoy   Generals :   Wellington   to   Roberts.      With  Portraits. 

Crown  Svo,  6s. 


12  William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 

FORSTER 

Where  Angels  Fear  to  Tread.     By  E.  M.  FORSTER.      Crown 

Svo,  6s. 

The  Longest  Journey.    Second  Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

FOULIS. 

Erchie :    My    Droll    Friend.      By    HUGH    FOULIS.      Paper 

covers,  6d. ;  cloth,  Is.  6d.  net. 

The  Vital  Spark.    Illustrated.    Is.  net 

FRASER. 

Philosophy  of  Theism.     Being  the  Gifford  Lectures  delivered 

before  the  University  of  Edinburgh  in  1894-96.  By  ALEXAXDM  CAMPBELL 
PHASER,  D.C.L.  Oxford;  Emeritus  Professor  of  Logic  and  Met* physics  in 
the  University  of  Edinburgh.  Second  Edition.  Revised.  Post  8vc,  6s.  6d.  net. 

Biographia  Philosophica.    In  1  vol.  demy  8vo,  6s.  net. 
FRASER.    The  Marches  of  Hindustan :  The  Record  of  a  Journey 

in  Thibet,  Trans-Himalayan  India,  Chinese  Turkestan,  Russian  Turkestan,  and 
Persia.  By  DAVID  FRASER.  With  Illustrations,  Maps,  and  Sketches.  Demy 
Svo,  £1,  Is.  net. 

FRENCH  COOKERY  FOR  ENGLISH  HOMES.     Third  Im- 
pression.   Crown  Svo,  limp  cloth,  2s.  6d.    Also  in  limp  leather,  3s. 

FULTON.    The  Sovereignty  of  the  Sea.    An  Historical  Account 

of  the  Claims  to  the  exclusive  Dominion  of  the  British  Seas  and  of  the  Evolu- 
tion of  the  Territorial  Waters,  with  special  reference  to  the  Rights  of  Fishing. 
By  T.  WKMTSS  PULTON,  M.D.,  F.R.S.E.  With  numerous  Illustrations  and  Maps. 
Demy  Svo.  [/»  the  press. 

GENERAL  ASSEMBLY  OF  THE  CHURCH  OF  SCOTLAND. 
Scottish  Hymnal,  With  Appendix  Incorporated.     Published 

for  use  in  Churches  by  Authority  of  the  General  Assembly,  i.  Large  type, 
cloth,  red  edges,  2s.  6d.;  French  morocco,  is.  3.  Bourgeois  type,  limp  cloth,  Is. ; 
French  morocco,  SB.  S.  Nonpareil  type,  cloth,  red  edges,  6d.;  French  morocco, 
Is.  4d.  4.  Paper  covers,  3d.  5.  Sunday -School  Edition,  paper  covers,  Id., 
cloth,  2d.  No.  1,  bound  with  the  Psalms  and  Paraphrases,  French  morocco,  8s. 
Nc.  2,  bound  with  the  Psalms  and  Pmrap  rases,  cloth,  2s.;  French  morocco,  Ss. 

Prayers  for  Social  and   Family   Worship.      Prepared   by   a 

Special  Committee  of  the  General  Assembly  of  the  Church  of  Scotland.  Entirely 
New  Edition,  Revised  and  Enlarged.  Fcap.  Svo.  red  edges.  Is.  6d.  net. 

Prayers  for  Family  Worship.      A  Selection  of  Four  Weeks' 

Prayers.  New  Edition.  Authorised  by  the  General  Assembly  of  the  Church  of 
Scotland.  Fcap.  Svo,  red  edges  Is.  net. 

One  Hundred  Prayers.     Prepared  by  the  Committee  on  Aids 

to  Devotion.     16mo,  cloth  limp,  64. 

Morning  and  Evening  Prayers  for  Affixing  to  Biblea,    Prepared 

by  the  Committee  on  Aids  to  Devotion.     Id.  for  6,  or  Is.  per  100. 

Prayers  for  Soldiers.    Prepared  by  the  Committee  on  Aids  to 

Devotion.    Seventieth  Thousand.     16mo,  cloth  limp.     2d.  net. 

Prayers  for  Sailors  and  Fisher-Folk.     Prepared  and  Published 

by  Instruction  of  the  General  Assembly  of  the  Church  of  Scotland.  Fcap.  Svo,  Is. 
net. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons.  13 


GERARD. 

Reata :    What's  in  a  Name.      By  E.    D.    GBRARD.      Cheap 

Edition.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  fid. 

Beggar  my  Neighbour.    Cheap  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  3a.  6d. 
The  Waters  of  Hercules.    Cheap  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 
A  Sensitive  Plant.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6cL 

GERARD. 

Honour's  Glassy  Bubble.    By  E.  GERARD.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 
A  Foreigner.    An  Anglo-German  Study.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

GERARD. 

One  Year.      By  DOROTHEA    GERARD  (Madame  Longard  de 

Longgarde).     Crown  8vo,  6s. 

The  Impediment.     Crown  8vo,  6s, 

A  Spotless  Reputation.    Third  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  6a. 

The  Wrong  Man.     Second  Edition.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Lady  Baby.     Cheap  Edition.     Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

Recha.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

A  Forgotten  Sin.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

GIBBON. 

Souls  in  Bondage.     By  PERCEVAL  GIBBON.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Cheap  Edition,  royal  8vo,  paper  cover,  6d. 

The  Vrouw  Grobelaar's  Leading  Cases.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 
GILL.    The  CHC13- Problem.    By  RICHARD  GILL.    2  vols.  crown 

8vo,  5s.  net  each. 

GILLANDERS.     Forest  Entomology.     By  A.  T.  GILLANDERS, 

F.E.S.    With  Illustrations.    Crown  8vo,  15s.  net. 

GLASGOW  BALLAD  CLUB.    Ballads  and  Poems.     By  MEM- 

BBRS  OF  THE  GLASGOW  BALLAD  CLUB.    Third  Series.    Crown  8vo.,  7s.  6d.  net. 

GLEIG.     The  Subaltern.     By  Rev.  G.  R.  GLEIG.     Fcap.  8vo, 

Is.  net. 

GRAHAM. 

Manual  of  the  Elections  (Scot.)  (Corrupt  and  Illegal  Practices) 

Act,  1890.  With  Analysis,  Relative  Act  of  Sederunt,  Appendix  containing  the 
Corrupt  Practices  Acts  of  1883  and  1885,  and  Oopiona  Index.  By  J.  HOWARD 
GRAHAM,  Advocate.  8vo,  4s.  6d. 

A  Manual  of  the  Acts  relating  to  Education  in  Scotland. 

(Pounded  on  that  of  the  late  Mr  Craig  Sellar.)    Demy  8vo,  18s. 

GRAHAM  AND  PATERSON.    True  Romances  of  Scotland.     By 

E.  MAXTONE  GRAHAM  and  E.  PATERSON.    Illustrations.    Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

GRAND. 

A  Domestic   Experiment.      By  SARAH  GRAND,    Author  of 

1  The  Heavenly  Twins,'  '  Ideala :  A  Study  from  Life.1    Crown  8vo,  8«. 

Singularly  Deluded.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 

GREY.  Poems.  By  DULCIBELLA  ETHEL  GREY.  With  a  Prefa- 
tory Note  by  H.  Cholmondeley  Pennell.  Demy  8vo.  Vellum,  12s.  6d.  net ;  half 
vellum,  7s .  6d.  net. 


14  William  Black-wood  &  Sons. 

GREEK. 

In  Furthest  Ind.    The  Narrative  of  Mr  EDWARD  CAKLYON  of 

Ells  wether,  In  the  County  of  Northampton,  and  late  of  the  Honourable  East  India 
Company's  Service,  Gentleman.  Wrote  by  his  own  hand  in  the  year  of  grace  1697. 
Edited,  with  a  few  Explanatory  Notes.  By  SYDNEY  C.  GRIER.  Post  Svo,  6s. 

His  Excellency's  English  Governess.    Third  Impression.     Cr. 

Svo,  8s. 

An  Uncrowned  King :  A  Romance  of  High  Politics.    Third 

Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Peace  with  Honour.     Third  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

A  Crowned  Queen:   The  Romance  of  a  Minister  of  State. 

Third  Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Like  Another  Helen.     Second  Impression     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
The   Kings  of  the  East :   A  Romance  of  the  near  Future. 

Second  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Warden  of  the  Marches.      Third  Impression.      Crown 

Svo,  6s.    Cheap  Edition,  paper  cover,  6d. 

The  Prince  of  the  Captivity.     Second  Impression.     Crown 

Svo,  6s. 

The  Advanced-Guard.    Third  Impression.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
The  Great  Proconsul :   The  Memoirs  of  Mrs  Hester  Ward, 

formerly  in  the  family  of  the  Hon.  Warren  Hastings,  Esquire,  late  Governor- 
General  of  India.  Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Heir.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Power  of  the  Keys.    With  Illustrations  by  A.  PEARCE. 

Third  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

The  Letters  of  Warren  Hastings  to  his  Wife.    Demy  Svo, 

6s.  net 

GRIERSON.      The  First   Half  of    the    Seventeenth    Century. 

(Periods  of  European  Literature.)  By  Professor  H.  J.  C.  GBIERSON.  Crown 
Svo,  5s.  net. 

GRIFFIN. 

Lady  Sarah's  Deed  of  Gift.    By  E.  ACEITTJNA  GRIFFIN.    Crown 

Svo,  6s. 

A  Servant  of  the  King.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

HAMLEY. 

The    Operations  of    War    Explained    and    Illustrated.      By 

General  Sir  EDWABD  BRUCK  HAMLBY,  K.C.B.,  K.O.M.G.  Second  Edition  of 
Fifth  Edition.  With  Haps  and  Plans.  4 to,  30s.  Also  in  2  parts:  Part  I., 
10s.  6d. ;  Part  II.,  21s. 

A  New  Edition,  brought  up  to  the  latest  requirements.     By 

Colonel  L.  E.  KIGGELL.    4to,  with  Maps  and  Plans,  30s. 

Thomas  Carlyle :   An  Essay.     Second   Edition.     Crown   Svo, 

3s.  6d. 

On  Outposts.     Second  Edition.     Svo,  2s. 

Lady  Lee's  Widowhood,     .New  Edition,     Crown  Svo,  2s. 

Our  Poor  Relations.     A  Philozoic  Essay.     With  Illustrations, 

Chiefly  by  Ernest  Griset.    Crown  Svo,  cloth  gilt,  3s.  6d. 

H  ANN  AY.     The    Later    Renaissance.     "  Periods  of  European 

Literature."    By  DAVID  HASSAY.    Crown  Svo,  5s.  net 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


HARRADEN. 

Ships  that  Pass  in  the  Night.     By    BEATRICE  HARRADEN. 

Illustrated  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

The  Fowler.     Illustrated  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d.    Cheap 

Edition,  paper  cover,  6d. 

In  Varying   Moods:    Short    Stories.       Illustrated    Edition. 

Crown  8vo,  8s.  6d. 

Untold  Tales  of  the  Past.  With  40  Illustrations  by  H.  R.  Millar. 

Square  crown  8vo,  gilt  top,  5s.  net. 

Katharine    Frensham.      Crown    8vo,    6s.      Cheap    Edition, 

paper  cover,  6d. 

HARTLEY.    Wild  Sport  with  Gun,  Rifle,  and  Salmon-Rod.    By 

GILFRID  W.  HARTLEY.  With  numerous  Illustrations  in  photogravure  and  half- 
tone from  drawings  by  G.  B.  LODGE  and  others.  Demy  8vo,  6s.  net. 

HAY.    "  Pip."    By  IAN  HAY.    Third  Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 
HAYLLAR.     Nepenthes.     By    FLORENCE    HAYLLAR.     Second 

Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

HEMANS. 

Select  Poems  of  Mrs  Hemans.    Fcap.,  cloth,  gilt  edges,  3a. 

HENDERSON.      The    Young    Estate    Manager's    Guide.      By 

RICHARD  HENDERSON,  Member  (by  Examination)  of  the  Royal  Agricultural 
Society  of  England,  the  Highland  and  Agricultural  Society  of  Scotland,  and 
the  Surveyors'  Institution.  With  an  Introduction  by  R.  Patrick  Wright, 
F.R.S.E.,  Professor  of  Agriculture,  Glasgow  and  West  of  Scotland  Technical 
College.  With  Plans  and  Diagrams.  Crown  8vo,  5s. 

HENDERSON.    The  Minstrelsy  of  the  Scottish  Border.    By  Sir 

WALTER  SCOTT.  A  New  Edition.  Edited  by  T.  P.  Henderson,  Author  of '  A 
History  of  Scottish  Vernacular  Literature.'  With  a  New  Portrait  of  Sir  Walter 
Scott.  In  4  vols.,  demy  8vo,  £2,  2s.  net. 

HERFORD.    Browning  (Modern  English  Writers).    By  Professor 

HERFORD.    Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

HERKLESS  AND  HANNAY. 

The  College  of  St  Leonard's.     By  Professor  HERKLESS  and 

ROBERT  KERR  HANNAY.    Post  8vo,  7s.  6d.  net. 

The  Archbishops  of  St  Andrews.    Vol.  I.    Demy  8vo,  7s.  6d.  net. 
HINTS  ON  HOCKEY.    With  Plans  and  Rules.    New  Edition. 

Pcap.  8vo,  Is. 

HOME  PRAYERS.    By  Ministers  of  the  Church  of  Scotland 

and  Members  of  the  Church  Service  Society.    Second  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo,  SB. 

HOPE.    A  History  of  the  1900  Parliament.    By,  JAMES  F.  HOPE. 

In  two  volumes.    Vol.  I.  ready.    Crown  8vo,  7s.  6d.  net. 

HUME.     The  Globular  Jottings  of  Griselda.     By  E.  DOUGLAS 

HUME.    With  Illustrations.    Demy  8vo,  10s.  net. 


1 6  William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


HUME.     Dialogues  concerning  Natural  Religion.     By  DAVID 

HCME.     Reprinted,  with  an  Introduction  by  BRUCE  M'EwKX,  D.PhiL    Crown 
Svo,  3s.  6d.  net. 

HUTCHINSON.    Hints  on  the  Game  of  Golf.    By  HORACE  G. 

HCTCHTSSOX.    Twelfth  Edition,  Revised.    Fcap.  Svo,  cloth,  Is. 

HUTTON.    Italy  and  the  Italians.   By  EDWARD  HUTTOX.    With 

Illustrations.    Second  Edition.    Large  crown  Svo,  6s. 


IDDESLEIGH.    Life,  Letters,  and  Diaries  of  Sir  Stafford  North- 

cote,  First  Earl  of  Iddesleigh.    By  ASDRJCW  LAXO.     With  Three  Portraits  and  « 
View  of  Pynes.    Third  Edition.    3  vols.  post  Svo,  Sis.  8d. 

POPULAR  EDITIOK.    With  Portrait  and  View  of  Pynes.    Post  Svo,  3s.  6d. 

INNES. 

Free  Church  Union  Case.    Judgment  of  the  House  of  Lords. 

With  Introduction  by  A.  TAYLOR  IXKKS,  IX.  D.     Demy  Svo,  Is.  net. 

The  Law  of  Creeds  in  Scotland.  A  Treatise  on  the  Rela- 
tions of  Churches  in  Scotland,  Established  and  not  Established,  to  the  Civil  Law. 
Demy  Svo,  10s.  net. 

INTELLIGENCE  OFFICER 

On  the  Heels  of  De  Wet.    By  THE  INTELLIGENCE  OFFICER. 

Sixth  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s.    Cheap  Edition  royal  Svo,  paper  cover,  6d. 

The  Boy  Galloper.    With  Illustrations.    In  1  vol.  cr.  Svo,  6s. 
The  Yellow  War.      Crown  Svo,  6s.      Cheap  Edition,  paper 

cover,  6d. 

A  Subaltern  of  Horse.    Second  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 
IRONS.     The  Psychology  of  Ethics.     By  DAVID  IRONS,  M.A., 

Ph.D.  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Bryn  Mawr  College,  Perm.    Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 


JAMES.      William    Wetmore    Story    and    his    Friends.      From 

Letters,  Diaries,  and  Recollections.    By  HKSEY  JAMES.    With  2  Portraits.    In 
two  vols.  post  Svo,  24s.  net. 

JAMES. 

Modern  Strategy.    By  Lieut-Col.  WALTER  EL  JAMES,  P.S.C., 

late   R.B.     With    6  Maps.    Second  Edition,  thoroughly  revised  and  brought 
up  to  date.    Royal  Svo,  16s.  net. 

The    Campaign   of  1815,  chiefly  in    Flanders.      With  Maps 

and  Plans.    Demy  Svo,  16s.  net. 

The  Development  of  Tactics  from  1740  to  the  Present  Day. 

Demy  Svo.  [7n  tt<  press. 

JOHNSTON. 

Elements  of  Agricultural  Chemistry.  An  entirely  New- 
Edition  from  the  Edition  by  Sir  CHARLKS  A.  CAMXRON.  M.D.,  F.R.C.8.I.  &c. 
Revised  and  brought  down  to  date  by  C.  M.  AUCMAH.  M.A.,  B.Sc.,  F.R.S.E.. 
Professor  of  Chemistry.  Glasgow  Vetericarv  College.  17th  Edition.  Crown  Svo, 
to.  M. 

Catechism  of  Agricultural  Chemistry.  An  entirely  Xew  Edi- 
tion from  'the  Edition  by  Sir  CHARLBS  A.  CAJTKRON.  Revised  and  Enlarged 
by  C.  M.  AirxAM  1C. A  &<".•  95th  Thousand.  With  numerous  Illustrations. 
Crown  Svo,  la. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons.  17 

JOHNSTON.     Agricultural  Holdings  (Scotland)  Acts,  1883  to 

1900 ;  and  the  Ground  Game  Act,  1880.  With  Notes,  and  Summary  of  Procedure, 
Ac.  By  CHRISTOPHER  N.  JOHNSTON,  M.A.,  Advocate.  Fifth  Edition.  Demy 
8vo,  6s.  net. 

JOKAI.    Timar's  Two  Worlds.    By  MATJRUS  JOKAI.    Authorised 

Translation  by  Mrs  HXGAN  KENNARD.    Cheap  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  68. 

KER.    The  Dark  Ages.    "  Periods  of  European  Literature."    By 

Professor  W.  P.  KER.    In  1  vol.  crown  8vo  5s.  net. 

KERR. 

Memories :    Grave  and  Gay.    By  JOHN  KERB,  LL.D.    With 

Portrait  and  other  Illustrations.  Cheaper  Edition,  Enlarged.  Crown  8vo, 
•2a.  Cd.  net. 

Other  Memories  :  Old  and  New.    Crown  8vo.     3s.  6d.  net. 

KINGLAKE. 

History  of  the  Invasion  of  the  Crimea.    By  A.  W.  KINGLAKB. 

Complete  in  9  vols.,  crown  Svo.    Cheap  reissue  at  3s.  6d.  each. 

Abridged  Edition  for  Military  Students.     Revised  by 

Lieut.-Col.  Sir  GEORGE  SYDENHAM  CLARKE,  K.C.M.G.,  R.E.  Demy  Svo,  15s.  net. 

Atlas  to  accompany  above.    Folio,  9s.  net. 

History  of  the  Invasion  of  the  Crimea.     Demy  Svo.    Vol.  VI. 

Winter  Troubles.  With  a  Map,  16s.  Vols.  VII.  and  VIII.  From  the  Morrow  of 
Inkerman  to  the  Death  of  Lord  Raglan.  With  an  Index  to  the  Whole  Work. 
With  Maps  and  Plans.  28s 

Eothen.    A  New  Edition,  uniform  with  the  Cabinet  Edition 

of  the  'History  of  the  Invasion  of  the  Crimea.1    6s. 

CHEAPER  EDITION.    With  Portrait  and  Biographical  Sketch  oi  the  Author. 
Crown  Svo,  2s.  fid.  net. 

KNEIPP.      My  Water -Cure.     As  Tested  through  more  than 

Thirty  Tears,  and  Described  for  the  Healing  of  Diseases  and  the  Preservation  of 
Health.  By  SEBASTIAN  ENEIFP.  With  a  Portrait  and  other  Illustrations. 
Authorised  English  Translation  from  the  Thirtieth  German  Edition,  by  A.  de  F. 
With  an  Appendix,  containing  the  Latest  Developments  of  Pfarrer  Kneipp's 
System,  and  a  Preface  by  E.  Gerard.  Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 

LANG. 

A  History  of  Scotland  from  the    Roman  Occupation.     By 

ANDREW  '  LANG.    Complete  in  Four  Volumes.    Demy  Svo,  £3,  3s.  net. 
VoL  I.     With  a  Photogravure  Frontispiece.     15s.  net. 
Vol.  II.    With  a  Photogravure  Frontispiece.    15s.  net. 
Vol.  III.    With  a  Photogravure  Frontispiece.     15s.  net. 
Vol.  IV.    With  a  Photogravure  Frontispiece.    20s.  net. 

Tennyson.   "Modern  English  Writers."  2nd  Ed.   Cr.  Svo,  2s.  6d. 
Life,  Letters,  and  Diaries  of  Sir  Stafford  Northcote,  First 

Earl  of  Iddesleigh.  With  Three  Portraits  and  a  View  of  Pynes.  Third  Edition. 
2  vols.  post  Svo,  31s.  6d. 

POPULAR  EDITION.    With  Portrait  and  View  of  Pynes.    Post  Svo,  3s.  6d. 

The  Highlands  of  Scotland  in  1750.     From  Manuscript  104 

in  the  King's  Library,  British  Museum.  With  an  Introduction  by  ANDREW  LANG. 
Grown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

LANG. 

The  Expansion  of  the  Christian  Life.      The  Duff  Lecture 

for  1897.  By  the  Rev.  J.  MARSHALL  LANQ,  D.D.,  Principal  of  the  University  of 
Aberdeen.  Crown  Svo,  5s. 

The  Church  and  its  Social  Mission.    Being  the  Baird  Lecture 

lor  1901.    Crown  Svo,  6s.  net. 


1 8  William  Black-wood  &  Sons. 


LAWSON. 

British  Economics.    By  W.  R.  LAWSON.    Crown  8vo,  6s.  net. 
American  Finance.    Second  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  6s.  net. 
John  Bull  and  His  Schools.    Crown  8vo,  5s.  net 

LEHMANN.    Crumbs  of  Pity,  and  other  Verses ;  to  which  are 

added  Six  Laves  of  Great  Men.  By  R.  C.  LKHMAXS,  author  of  '  Anni  Fugaces,' 
&c.  Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

LEIGHTON.     The  Life  History  of  British  Serpents,  and  their 

Local  Distribution  in  the  British  Isles.  By  GERALD  R.  LEIGHTON,  M.D.  With 
50  Illustrations.  Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

LEISHMAN.  The  Westminster  Directory.  Edited,  with  an  Intro- 
duction and  Notes,  by  the  Very  Rev.  T.  LEISHMAX,  D.  D.    Crown  8vo,  4s.  net. 

LINDSAY. 

Recent  Advances  in  Theistic  Philosophy  of  Religion.    By  Rev, 

JAMBS  LOTOAY,  M.A.,  D.D.,  B.Sc.,  F.R.S.E.,  F.G.8.,  Minister  of  the  Parish  of 
St  Andrew's,  Kilmarnock.  Demy  8vo,  12s  6d.  net. 

The  Progressiveness  of  Modern  Christian  Thomght.    Crown 

8vo,  6s. 

Essays,  Literary  and  Philosophical.     Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

The  Significance  of  the  Old  Testament  for  Modern  Theology. 

Grown  8vo,  Is.  net. 

The  Teaching  Function  of  the  Modern  PuJpit.    Crown  8vo, 

Is.  net 

LITURGIES     AND     ORDERS     OF     DIVINE     SERVICE 

(CHURCH    SERVICE    SOCIETY). 

The  Second  Prayer  Book  of  King  Edward  the  Sixth  (1552). 

With  Historical  Introduction  and  Notes  by  the  Rev.  H.  J.  WOTHERSPOON,  M.  A. , 
of  St  Oswald's  Edinburgh ;  and  THE  LITURGY  OF  COMPROMISE.  Used  in  the 
English  Congregation  mt  Frankfort.  From  an  Unpublished  MS.  Edited  by  the 
Rev.  G.  W.  SPROTT,  D.D.  4s.  net. 

Book  of  Common  Order.    Commonly  called  Knox's  Liturgy. 

Edited  by  Rev.  G.  W.  SPROTT,  D.D.    4s.  6d.  net. 

Scottish  Liturgies  of  the  Reign  of  James  VI.    Edited  by  Rev. 

G.  W.  SPROTT,  D.D.    4s.  net 

Liturgy  of  1637.     Commonly  called  Laud's  Liturgy.     Edited 

by  the  Rev.  Professor  COOPER,  D.D.    7s.  6d.  net. 

The  Westminster  Directory.    Edited  by  Very  Rev.  T.  LEISH- 

MAK,  D.D.    4s.  net. 

Euchologion.     A  Book  of  Common  Order :   Being  Forms  of 

Prayer,  and  Administration  of  the  Sacraments,  and  other  Ordinances  of  the 
Church.  Edited  by  the  Rev.  G.  W.  SPROTT,  D.D.  4s.  6d.  net. 

LOBBAN.    An  Anthology  of  English  Verse  from  Chaucer  to  the 

Present  Day.    By  J.  H.  LOBBAN,  M.A.    Crown  Svo,  gilt  top,  5s. 

LOCKHART. 

Doubles  and  Quits.    By  LAURENCE  W.  M.  LOCKHART.    Crown 

Svo,  3s.  6d. 

Fair  to  See.     Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 

Mine  is  Thine.     New  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons.  19 


LORIMER.    The  Author's  Progress  :   or,  The  Literary  Book  of 

the  Road.      By  ADAM  LORIMER.     Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

LYNDEN-BELL.     A  Primer  of  Tactics,  Fortification,  Topo- 

graphy, and  Military  Law.      By  Lieut.  -  Colonel  C.  P.  LYNDBN-BELL.     With 
Diagrams.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  net. 

MABIE. 

Essays  on  Nature  and  Culture.    By  HAMILTON  WRIGHT  MABIE. 

With  Portrait.    Fcap.  8vo,  8s.  6d. 

Books  and  Culture.    Fcap.  8vo,  3s.  6d. 
M'AULAY.    The  Safety  of  the  Honours.     By  ALLAN  M'AITLAY. 

Crown  8vo,  6s. 

M'CONACHIE.    Close  to  Nature's  Heart.    By  WILLIAM  M'CoN- 

ACHIE,  B.D.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d.  net 

MACDONALD.    A  Manual  of  the  Criminal  Law  (Scotland)  Pro 

cednre  Act,  1887.     By  NORMAK  DORAN  MACDONALD.      Revised  by  the  LORD 
8vo  10s.  6d 


MACKAY.    The  Return  of  the  Emigrant.    By  LYDIA  MILLER 

MACKAY.    Third  Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

MACKENZIE.     Studies  in  Roman  Law.     With   Comparative 

Views  of  the  Laws  of  France,  England,  and  Scotland.  By  LORD  MACKENZIE, 
one  of  the  Judges  of  the  Court  of  Session  in  Scotland.  Seventh  Edition,  Edited 
by  JOHN  KIRKPATRICK,  M.A.,  LL.D.,  Advocate,  Professor  of  History  in  the 
University  of  Edinburgh.  8vo,  2lH. 

MACKINLAY.    Garcia  the  Centenarian  :  and  his  Times.    Being 

a  Memoir  of  Don  Manuel  Garcia  s  Life  and  Labours  for  the  advancement  of 
Music  and  Science.  By  M.  STERLING  MACKINLAY,  M.A.  Oxon.  With  twenty 
Portraits.  Demy  8vo,  15s.  net. 

MACLEOD.     The  Doctrine  and  Validity  of  the  Ministry  and 

Sacraments  of  the  National  Church  of  Scotland.  By  the  Very  Rev.  DONALD 
MACLEOD,  D.D.  Being  the  Baird  Lecture  for  1903.  Crown  8vo,  6s.  net. 

MACNAMARA.    The  Trance.    By  RACHEL  SWETE  MACNAMARA. 

Crown  8vo,  6s. 

MACPHERSON. 

Books  to  Read  and  How  to  Read  Them.     By  HECTOR  MAC- 

PHERSON.   Second  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d.  net. 

A  Century's  Intellectual  Development.     Crown  Svo,  6s.  net. 
A  Century  of  Political  Development.     3s.  6d.  net. 

MACPHERSON. 

A   Century's    Progress    in  Astronomy.      By    HECTOR    MAC- 

PHERSON, Jun.    Short  demy  Svo,  6s.  net. 
Through    the    Depths  of   Space  :    A  Primer  of  Astronomy. 

Crown  Svo,  2s.  net. 

MAIR. 

A  Digest  of  Laws  and   Decisions,  Ecclesiastical  and  Civil, 

relating  to  the  Constitution,  Practice,  and  Affairs  of  the  Church  of  Scotland. 
With  Notes  and  Forms  of  Procedure.  By  the  Rev.  WILLIAM  MAIR,  D.D.,  lately 
Minister  of  the  Parish  of  Earlston.  New  Edition,  Revised.  In  1  vol.  crown  Svo, 
12s.  6d.  net. 

Speaking  ;  or,  From  Voice  Production  to  the  Platform   and 

Pulpit.    Third  Edition,  Revised.    Crown  Svo,  2s. 


2O  William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


MARSHMAN.     History  of  India.     From  the  Earliest  Period  to 

the  present  time.  By  Jomr  CLARK  MAMHMAH,  C.8.L  Third  and  Cheaper 
Bdition.  Post  8vo,  with  Map,  6s. 

MARTIN. 

Poems  of  Giacomo  Leopardi     Translated  by  Sir  THEODORE 

MABTIS,  K.C.B.     Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

The  iEneid  of  Virgil.     Books  L-VL    Translated  by  Sir  THEO 

DORK  MABTIS,  K.C.B.    Post  Svo,  7s.  fld. 

Goethe's  Faust.      Part  I.      Translated  into   English   Verse 

Second  Edition,  crown  Svo,  Os.     Ninth  Edition,  feap.  Svo,  3s.  6d- 

Goethe's  Faust.     Part  II.     Translated   into  English  Verse. 

Second  Edition,  Revised.     Fcap.  Svo,  6s. 

The  Works  of  Horace.    Translated  into  English  Verse,  with 

life  and  Notes.    8  rols.    New  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  Sis. 

Poems  and  Ballads  of  Heinrich  Heine.    Done  into  English 

Verse.    Third  Edition.    Small  crown  Svo,  5s. 

The  Song  of  the  Bell,  and  other  Translations  from  Schiller, 

Goethe,  TJhland,  and  Others.    Crown  Svo,  7s.  6d. 

Madonna  Pia  :  A  Tragedy  ;  and  Three  Other  Dramas.    Crown 

Svo.  7s.  Sd. 

Catullus.     With  Life  and  Notes.     Second  Edition,  Revised 

and  Corrected.    Port  Svo,  7s.  6d. 

The  '  Vita  Nuova '  of  Dante.    Translated  with  an  Introduction 

and  Note*.    Fourth  Edition,    Small  crown  Svo,  5s. 

Aladdin:  A  Dramatic  Poem.     By  ADAM  OBHLENSCHLAEGER 

Fcap.  Svo,  5s. 

Correggio  :  A  Tragedy.     By  OEHLENSCHLAEGER.    With  Notes. 

Fcap.  Svo,  3s. 

Helena  Faucit  (Lady  Martin).     By  Sir  THEODORE  MARTIN, 

K.C.B.,  K.C.V.O.  With  Five  Photogravure  Plates.  3econd  Edition.  Demy  Svo, 
10s.  64.  net. 

Poems  and  Ballads  of  Goethe.      By  Sir  THEODORE  MARTIN 

and  Professor  Arroux.  Third  Edition.  With  Introduction  by  Sir  THEODORK 
MABTIS.  Small  crown  Svo,  6s.  net. 

Queen  Victoria  as  I  Knew  Her.     Square  crown  Svo,  3s.  6d.  net. 
MARTIN.    On  some  of  Shakespeare's  Female  Characters.     By 

HELESA  FACCTT,  Lady  MARTI*.  Dedicated  by  permission  to  Her  Mott  Gracivtu 
Majettg  On  Queen.  With  a  Portrait  by  Lehmann.  Seventh  Edition,  with  a  new 
Preface.  Demy  Svo,  7s.  6d- 

MASEFIELD.      Gilbert    Hermer.      By    CHARLES    MASEFIELD. 

Crown  Svo,  6s. 

MASSOX.Jf  Memories  of  London  in  the  .Torties,     By  DAVID 

MASSOS.     Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d.  net 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons.  21 


MATHESON. 

Can  the  Old  Faith  Live  with  the  New  1  or,  The  Problem  of 

Evolution  and  Revelation.     By  the  Rev.  GEORGB  MATHESON,  D.D.    Third  Edi- 
tion.   Crown  8vo.  7s.  6d. 

The  Psalmist  and  the  Scientist ;  or,  Modern  Value  of  the  Reli- 
gions Sentiment.    Third  Edition.    Grown  8vo,  5s. 

Spiritual  Development  of  St  Paul.  Fourth  Edition.  Cr.  8vo,  5s. 

The  Distinctive  Messages  of  the  Old  Religions.    Second  Edi- 
tion.   Crown  Svo,  5s. 

Sacred  Songs.     Third  Edition.    Oqwn  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

MAXWELL. 

Dumfries    and    Galloway.      By   Right    Hon.    Sir   HERBERT 

MAXWELL,  Bart.    Being  one  of  the  Volumes  of  the  County  Histories  of  Scotland. 
With  Four  Maps.    Second  Edition.    Demy  8 vo,  7s.  (id.  net. 

Scottish  Land-Names  :   Their  Origin  and  Meaning.      Being 

the  Rhind  Lectures  in  Archaeology  for  1893.    Post  8vo,  6s. 

Holyrood,  Abbey  Church,  Palace,  and  Environs.    Crown  8vo. 

Paper  cover,  6d.  net ;  cloth,  2s.  6d.  net. 

MAXWELL.    In  Malay  Forests.    By  GEORGE  MAXWELL.    Crown 

8vo,  6s.  net. 

MELDRUM. 

The  Conquest  of  Charlotte.    By  DAVID  S.  MELDRUM.    Third 

Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Holland  and   the  Hollanders.    With  numerous  Illustrations 

and  a  Map.    Second  Edition.    Square  8vo,  6s. 

The  Story  of  Margre'del :  Being  a  Fireside  History  of  a  Fife. 

shire  Family.    Cheap  Edition     Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 

Grey  Mantle  and  Gold  Fringe.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

MELLONE. 

Studies  in  Philosophical  Criticism  and  Construction.      By 

SYDNEY  HERBERT  MELLONI,  M.A.  Lond.,  D.Sc.  Edin.    Post  Svo,  10s.  6d.  net. 

Leaders  of  Religious  Thought  in  the  Nineteenth  Century. 

Crown  Svo,  6s.  net. 

An  Introductory   Text-Book  of  Logic.      Third  Edition,  Re- 
vised.   Crown  Svo,  5s. 
Elements  of  Psychology.     Crown  Svo,  5s. 

MERZ.    A  History  of  European  Thought  in  the  Nineteenth  Cen- 
tury.    By  JOHN  THKODORK   MER*.     Vol.  I.     Third  Impression.     Post  Svo, 
10s.  fid.  net. 
Vol.  II.,  15s.  net. 

MEYNELL.    John  Ruskin.    "  Modern  English  Writers."    By  Mrs 

MEYNBLL.    Third  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

MICHIE.    The  Englishman  in  China  during  the  Victorian  Era. 

As  Illustrated  in  the  Life  of  Sir  Rutherford  Alcock,  K.C.B.,  D.O.L.  By  ALEX- 
ANDER MICHIE.  With  Illustrations,  Portraits,  and  Maps.  2  vols.  demy  Svo,  38s. 
net. 

MICKLETHWAIT.     The  Licensing  Act,   1904.      By  St  J.  G. 

MICKLETHWAIT,  M.A.,  B.C.L.,  Barrister-at-Law.    Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d.  net. 


22  William  Black-wood  &  Sons. 


MILL. 

The  Colonel  Sahib.     A  Novel.    By  GARRETT  MILL.     Second 

Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Ottavia.    Second  Impression.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 
Mr  Montgomery  :  Fool.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 
In  the  Hands  of  the  Czar.     Crown  8vo,  6s 
The  Cardinal's  Secret.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

MILLAR.    The  Mid-Eighteenth  Century.    "  Periods  of  European 

Literature."    By  J.  H.  MIELAR.     Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

MITCHELL.      The    Scottish   Reformation.     Being   the    Baird 

Lecture  for  1899.  By  the  late  ALEXANDER  F.  MITCHELL,  D.D.,  LL.D.  Edited 
by  D.  HAY  FLEMING,  LL.D.  With  a  Biographical  Sketch  of  the  Author,  by 
James  Christie,  D.D.  Crown  8vo.  6«. 

MITCHELL.     Significant   Etymology.      By  Rev.  JAMES    MIT- 
CHELL, D.D.    Short  demy  8vo,  7s.  6d.  net. 

MODERN    ENGLISH    WRITERS.      In    handy    crown    8vo 

volumes,  tastefully  bound,  price  2s.  6d.  each. 

Matthew  Arnold.     By  Professor  SAINTSBURY.     Second  Im- 

Eession. 
.  Stevenson.    By  L.  COPE  CORXFORD.    Second  Impression. 
John  Ruskin.    By  Mrs  MEYNELL.    Third  Impression. 
Tennyson.      By  ANDREW  LANO.    Second  Edition. 
Huxley.    By  EDWARD  CLODD. 
Thackeray.    By  CHARLES  WHIBLEY. 
Browning.    By  Prof.  C.  H.  HBRFORD. 

tfOIR.     Life  of  Mansie  Wauch,  Tailor  in  Dalkeith.     By  D.  M. 

MOIR.    With  CRUIKSHANK'S  Illustrations.    Cheaper  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

MOMERIE. 

Dr  Alfred  Momerie.    His  Life  and  Work.    By  Mrs  MOMERIE. 

Demy  8vo,  12s.  6d.  net. 

The  Origin  of  Evil,  and  other  Sermons.     By  Rev.  ALFRED 

WILLIAMS  HOMKBIK,  M.A.,  D.Sc.,  LL.D.  Eighth  Edition,  Enlarged.  Crown 
8vo,  5s. 

Personality.   The  Beginning  and  End  of  Metaphysics,  and  a  Ne- 
cessary Assumption  in  all  Positive  Philosophy.    Fifth  Ed.,  Revised.   Cr.  8vo,  Sg. 

Agnosticism.    Fourth  Edition,  Revised.    Crown  8vo,  5s. 
Preaching  and  Hearing  ;  and  other  Sermons.   Fourth  Edition, 

Enlarged.    Crown  8vo,  5a. 

Belief  in  God.     Fourth  Edition.     Crown  8vo,  3s. 

The  Future  of  Religion,  and  other  Essays.    Second  Edition. 

Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

The  English  Church  and  the  Romish  Schism.    Second  Edition. 

Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

Essays  on  the  Bible.    Crown  8vo.  [In  the  press. 


William  Blackwood  &•  Sons.  23 


MONTAGUE.     Military  Topography.     Illustrated  by  Practical 

Examples  of  a  Practical  Subject.  By  Major-General  W.  B.  MONTAGUE,  C.B., 
P.S.C.,  late  Garrison  Instructor  Intelligence  Department,  Author  of  '  Campaign- 
in?  in  South  Africa.1  With  Forty-one  Diagrams.  Crown  8vo,  5s. 

MUNRO.    The  Daft  Days.    Third  Impression.   By  NEIL  MUNRO- 

Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Uniform  Edition  Novels. 
John  Splendid.    The  Tale  of  a  Poor  Gentleman  and  the  Little 

Wars  of  Lorn.    Sixth  Impression.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

Children  of  Tempest :  A  Tale  of  the  Outer  Isles.     Crown 

8vo,  3s.  6d. 

Shoes  of  Fortune.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

The    Lost    Pibroch,    and    other    Shelling    Stories.    Fourth 

Impression.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

Doom    Castle :    A   Romance.      Second   Impression.     Crown 

Svo,  3s.  6d. 

Gilian  the  Dreamer.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

MUNRO. 

Rambles  and  Studies  in  Bosnia-Herzegovina  and  Dalmatia. 

By  ROBERT  MUNRO,  M.A.,  M.D.,  LL.D.,  F.R.8.E.  Second  Edition,  Revised 
and  Enlarged.  With  numerous  illustrations.  Demy  8vo,  12s.  6d.  net. 

Prehistoric  Problems.    With  numerous  Illustrations.    Demy 

Svo,  10s.  net. 

MUNRO.     On  Valuation  of  Property.    By  WILLIAM  MUNBO, 

M.A.,  Her  Majesty's  Assessor  of  Railways  and  Canals  for  Scotland.  Second 
Edition,  Revised  and  Enlarged.  Svo,  3s.  «d. 

MYRES.    A  Manual  of  Classical  Geography.    By  JOHN  L.  MYRES. 

Crown  Svo.  [In  the  press. 


NEWCOMBE.     Village,  Town,  and  Jungle  Life  in  India.     By 

A.  C.  NEWCOMBE.    Demy  8vo,  12s.  6d.  net. 

NICHOLSON  AND  LYDEKKER. 

A  Manual  of  Palaeontology,  for  the  Use  of  Students.    With  a 

General  Introduction  on  the  Principles  of  Palaeontology.  By  Professor  H. 
ALLKTNK  NICHOLSON  and  RICHARD  LYDEKKER,  B.A.  Third  Edition,  entirely 
Rewritten  and  greatly  Enlarged.  2  vols.  Svo,  £3,  SB. 

NICOL. 

Recent    Archaeology    and    the    Bible.     Being    the    Croall 

Lectures  for  1898.  By  the  Rev.  THOMAS  NICOL,  D.D.,  Professor  of  Divinity 
and  Biblical  Criticism  in  the  University  of  Aberdeen ;  Author  of  '  Recent  Ex- 
plorations in  Bible  Lands.'  Demy  Svo,  9s.  net. 

The  Four  Gospels  in  the  Earliest  Church  History.    Being  the 

Baird  Lecture  for  1907.    Crown  Svo,  7s.  6d.  net. 

N1SBET.    The  Forester  :  A  Practical  Treatise  on  British  Forestry 

and  Arboriculture  for  Landowners,  Land  Agents,  and  Foresters.  By  JOHN 
NISBET,  D.CKc.  In  2  volumes,  royal  Svo,  with  285  Illustrations,  42s.  net. 

NOBILI.      A    Modern    Antique:    A    Florentine    Story.      By 

RICCASDO  NOBILI.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 


24  William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 

NOBLR 

The  Edge  of  Circumstance.    By  EDWARD  NOBLE.    Crown  8vo, 

6s.    Cheap  Edition,  royal  8vo,  paper  cover,  6d. 

Waves  of  Fate.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 

Fisherman's  Gat :  A  Story  of  the  Thames  Estuary.    Crown 

Svo,  6a. 

The  Grain  Carriers.    Third  Impression.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 

NOTES. 

Poems  by  ALFRED  NOTES.    7s.  6d.  net. 

The  Forest  of  Wild  Thyme :  A  Tale  for  Children  under  Ninety. 

Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

Drake :  An  English  Epic.    Books  I. -III.    Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 
Forty  Singing  Seamen.    Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 


0.    The  Yellow  War.    By  O.    Crown  Svo,  6s.     Cheap  Edition. 

Royal  Svo,  6d. 

OLIPHANT. 

Piccadilly.    With  Illustrations  by  Richard  Doyle.    New  Edi- 
tion, 3s.  6d.    Cheap  Edition,  boards,  2s.  6d. 

Episodes  in  a  Life  of  Adventure;  or,  Moss  from  a  Rolling 

Stone.    Cheaper  Edition.    Post  Svo,  Ss.  6d. 

OLIPHANT. 

Annalg  of  a  Publishing  House.    William  Blackwood  and  his 

Sons ;  Their  Magazine  and  Friends.    By  Mrs  OLTPHAST.    With  Four  Portraiti. 
Third  Edition.    Demy  Svo.    Vols.  I.  and  II.  £2,  2s. 

A  Widow's  Tale,  and  other  Stories.    With  an  Introductory 

Note  by  J.  M.  BABBIK.    Second  Edition.    Grown  Svo,  6s. 

Katie  Stewart,  and  other  Stories.     New  Edition.    Crown  Svo, 
cloth,  Ss.  64. 

Katie  Stewart.    Illustrated  boards,  2s.  6d. 
Valentine  and  his  Brother.    New  Edition,    Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 
Sons  and  Daughters.    Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 
OMOND.     The    Romantic    Triumph.      "Periods   of   European 

Literature."    By  T.  S.  OMOND.    Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

O'NEILL.    Songs  of  the  Glens  of  Antrim.     By  MOIRA  O'NEILL. 

Twelfth  Impression.    Crown  Svo  3s.  6d. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons.  25 


PAGE. 

Intermediate  Text-Book  of  Geology.    By  Professor  LAPWOKTH. 

Founded  on  Dr  Page's  '  Introductory  Text- Book  of  Geology.'    Crown  8vo,  5s. 

Advanced  Text-Book  of  Geology.    New  Edition.    Revised  and 

enlarged  by  Professor  LAPWORTH.    Crown  8vo.  [In  the  press. 

Introductory  Text  -  Book  of   Physical   Geography.      Crown 

8vo,  2s.  6d. 

Advanced  Text-Book  of  Physical  Geography.    Crown  8vo,  5s. 
Physical  Geography  Examinator.    Crown  8vo,  sewed,  9d. 

PARKER.     Miss    Lomax :    Millionaire.      By   BESSIE    PARKER. 

Crown  8vo,  6s. 

PATERSON.    Peggotts ;  or,  The  Indian  Contingent.    By  MAR- 

GAHET  PATERSON.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

PAUL.    History  of  the  Royal  Company  of  Archers,  the  Queen's 

Body-Guard  for  Scotland.  By  Sir  JAMES  BALFOUR  PAUL,  Advocate  of  the  Scottish 
Bar.  Crown  4to,  with  Portraits  and  other  Illustrations.  £2,  38. 

PEARSE. 

The  Hearseys :  Five  Generations  of  an  Anglo-Indian  Family. 

By  Colonel  HUGH  PEARSE,  D.S.O.    Demy  8vo,  15s.  net. 

Memoir  of  the  Life  and  Military  Services  of  Viscount  Lake, 

Baron  Lake  of  Delhi  and  Laswaree,  1744-1808.  With  Portraits,  &c.  Demy  8vo, 
15s.  net. 

PEILE.     Clanbrae:    A  Golfing   Idyll.     By    PENTLAND    PEILE. 

Crown  8vo,  6s. 

PERIODS  OF  EUROPEAN  LITERATURE.    Edited  by  Pro- 

fessor  SAINTSBDRY.  -  For  List  of  Volumes,  tee  page  2. 

PHILOSOPHICAL  CLASSICS  FOR  ENGLISH  READERS. 

Edited  by  WILLIAM  KNIGHT,  LL.D.,  Professor  of  Moral  Philosophy,  University 

of  St  Andrews.    Cheap  Re-issue  in  Shilling  Volumes  net. 

[For  List  of  Volumes,  see  page  2. 

POLLOK.    The  Course  of  Time  :  A  Poem.    By  ROBKET  POLLOK, 

A.M.    New  Edition.    With  Portrait.    Fcap.  8vo,  gilt  top,  SB.  6d. 

PRINGLE-PATTISON. 

Scottish  Philosophy.     A  Comparison  of   the  Scottish    and 

German  Answers  to  Hume.  Balfour  Philosophical  Lectures,  University  of 
Edinburgh.  By  A.  SETH  PRINGLE-PATTISON,  LL.D.,  D.C.L.,  Fellow  of  the 
British  Academy,  Professor  ol  Logic  and  Metaphysics  in  Edinburgh  University. 
Fourth  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  5s. 

Hegelianism  and  Personality.    Balfour  Philosophical  Lectures. 

Second  Series.    Second  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  5s. 

Man's  Place  in  the  Cosmos,  and  other  Essays.   Second  Edition, 

Enlarged.    Post  8vo,  6s.  net 


26  William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


PRINGLE-PATTISON. 

Two  Lectures  on  Theism.     Delivered  on  the  occasion  of  the 

Sesquicentennial  Celebration  ot  Princeton  University.    Crown  8vo,  2s   6d. 

The    Philosophical    Radicals    and    Other   Essays,    including 

Chapters  reprinted  on  the  Philosophy  of  .Religion  in  Kant  and  HegeL    Crown 
8vo,  6s.  net. 

PUBLIC  GENERAL  STATUTES  AFFECTING  SCOTLAND 

from  1707  to  1847,  with  Chronological  Table  and  Index.     3  vols.  large  8vo,  £3,  3s. 
Also  Published  Annually  with  General  Index. 

RANJITSINHJI.    The  Jubilee  Book  of  Cricket.    By  PBINCE 

RAJJJITSINHJI. 
POPULAR  EDITION.  With  107  fall-page  Illustrations.  Sixth  Edition.  Large 

crown  8vo,  6s. 
SIXPENNY  EDITION.  With  a  selection  of  the  Illustrations. 

ROBERTSON. 

Early  Religions  of  Israel.    New  and  Revised  Edition.    Crown 

8vo.  [In  the  press. 

The  Poetry  and  the  Religion  of  the  Psalms.    The  Croall 

Lectures,  1893-94.    By  JAMKS  ROBKKTSON,  D.D.,  Professor  of  Oriental  Languages 
in  the  University  of  Glasgow.    Demy  Svo,  12s. 

ROBERTSON. 

A  History  of  German  Literature.    By  JOHN  G.  ROBERTSON, 

Ph.D.,  Professor  of  German,  University  of  London.    Demy  Svo,  10s.  6d.  net. 

Schiller  after  a  Century.    Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d.  net. 

RONALDSHAY. 

On  the  Outskirts  of  Empire  in  Asia.      By  the   EAEL  OF 

RONALDSHAY,    M.P.     With    numerous    Illustrations   and    Maps.      Royal  Svo, 
218.  net 

Sport  and  Politics  under  an  Eastern  Sky.      With  numerous 

Illustrations  and  Maps.    Royal  Svo,  21s.  net. 

RUTLAND. 

Notes  of  an  Irish  Tour  in  1846.    By  the  DUKB  OF  RUTLAND, 

G.C.B.  (LORD  JOHN  MANNERS).     New  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

Correspondence   between   the  Right   Honble.   William   Pitt 

and  Charles  Duke  of  Rutland,  Lord-Lieutenant  of  Ireland,  1781-1787.    With 
Introductory  Note  by  JOHN  DUKK  OF  RUTLAND.    Svo,  7s.  6d. 

The  Collected  Writings  of  Janetta,  Duchess  of  Rutland.    With 

Portrait  and  Illustrations.     2  vols.  post  Svo,  15s.  net. 

Impressions  of  Bad-Homburg.    Comprising  a  Short  Account 

of  the  Women's  Associations  of  Germany  under  the  Red  Cross.    By  the  DUCHESS 
OF  RUTLAND  (LADY  JOHN  MANNHRS).    Crown  Svo,  Is.  6d. 

Some  Personal  Recollections  of  the  Later  Years  of  the  Earl 

of  Beaconsfield,  K.G.    Sixth  Edition.    6d. 

Employment  of  Women  in  the  Public  Service.    6d. 

Some  of  the  Advantages  of  Easily  Accessible  Reading  and 

Recreation  Rooms  and  Free  Libraries.    With  Remarks  on  Starting  and  Main- 
taining them.     Second  Edition.    Crown  Svo,  Is. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons.  27 

RUTLAND. 

A  Sequel  to  Rich  Men's  Dwellings,  and  other  Occasional 

Papers.    Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d. 

Encouraging  Experiences  of  Reading  and  Recreation  Rooms, 

Aims  of  Guilds,  Nottingham  Social  Guide,  Bzisting  Institutions,  &c.,  &c. 
Crown  8vo,  Is. 

SAINTSBURY. 

A  History  of  Criticism  and  Literary  Taste  in  Europe.    From 

the  Earliest  Texts  to  the  Present  Day.  By  GEORGE  SAINTSBURY,  M.A.  (Oxon.) 
Hon.  LL.D.  (Aberd.),  Professor  of  Rhetoric  and  English  Literature  in  the  Univer 
sity  of  Edinburgh.  In  3  vols.  demy  8vo.  Vol.  I.— Classical  and  Mediaeval  Criti- 
cism. 16s.  net. 

Vol.  II. — Prom  the  Renaissance  to  the  Decline  of  Eighteenth  Century  Ortho- 
doxy.   20s.  net. 
Vol.  III. — Nineteenth  Century.    20s.  net. 

Matthew  Arnold.    "Modern  English  Writers."    Second  Edi- 
tion.   Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d 

The  Flourishing  of  Romance  and  the  Rise  of  Allegory  (12th 

and  18th  Centuries).    "Periods  of  European  Literature."    Crown  8vo,  5s.  net, 

The  Earlier  Renaissance.     "  Periods  of  European  Literature." 

Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

The    Later    Nineteenth    Century.       "Periods    of   European 

Literature."    Crown  8vo,  5s.  net 

"SCOLOPAX."       A    Book    of    the    Snipe.       By    SCOLOPAX. 

Illustrated.    Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

SCOTT.    Tom  Cringle's  Log.    By  MICHAEL  SCOTT.    New  Edition. 

With  19  Pull-page  Illustrations.    Crown  8vo,  8s.  6d. 

SCUDAMORE.    Belgium  and  the  Belgians.    By  CYBIL  SCTTDA- 

MORE.    With  Illustrations.    Square  crown  8vo,  6s. 

SELLAR.    Recollections  and  Impressions.     By  E.  M.  SELLAR. 

With  Eight  Portraits.    Fourth  Impression.    Demy  8vo,  10s.  6d.  net. 

SELLAR.    Muggins  of  the  Modern  Side.    By  EDMUND  SELLAR. 

Crown  8vo,  6s. 

SETH.    A  Study  of  Ethical  Principles.    BY  JAMES  SETH,  M.A., 

Professor  of  Moral  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Edinburgh.  Eighth  Edition, 
Revised.  Post  8vo,  7s.  6d. 

SHARPLEY.     Aristophanes — Pax.     Edited,  with  Introduction 

and  Notes,  by  H.  SHARPLEY.    Demy  8vo,  12s.  6d.  net. 

SHAW.    Securities  over  Moveables.    Four  Lectures  delivered  at 

the  Request  of  the  Society  of  Accountants  in  Edinburgh,  the  Institute  of  Ac- 
countants and  Actuaries  in  Glasgow,  and  the  Institute  of  Bankers  in  Scotland, 
in  1902-3.  Demy  8vo,  3s.  6d.  net. 

SILLERY.    A  Curtain  of  Cloud.    By  Major  C.  SILLERY.    Crown 

Svo,  6s. 

SIMPSON.    Side-Lights  on  Siberia.    Some  account  of  the  Great 

Siberian  Iron  Road:  The  Prisons  and  Exile  System.  By  Professor  J.  Y. 
SIMPSON,  D.Sc.  With  numerous  Illustrations  and  a  Map.  Demy  Svo,  16s. 


28  William  Blackwood  &  Sons. 


SKELTON.    The  Handbook  of  Public  Health.    A  New  Edition, 

Revised  by  JAMES  PATTEX  MACDOUOAJ.L,  Advocate,  Secretary  to  the  Local 
Government  Board  for  Scotland,  Joint -Author  of  '  The  Parish  Council  Guide  for 
Scotland,'  and  ABIJAH  MURRAY,  Chief  Clerk  of  the  Local  Government  Board  for 
Scotland.  In  Two  Parts.  Crown  8vo.  Pan  I.— The  Public  Health  (Scotland) 
Act,  1897,  with  Notes.  3s.  6d.  net. 

SKRINE.    Fontenoy,  and  Great  Britain's  share  in  the  War  of  the 

Austrian  Succession.  By  F.  H.  SKRINE.  With  Map,  Plans,  and  Illustrations. 
Demy  8vo,  21s.  net 

SMITH. 

The  Transition  Period.     "Periods  of  European  Literature." 

By  G.  GREGORY  SMITH.    Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

Specimens  of  Middle  Scots.    Post  8vo,  7s.  6d.  net. 
SMITH.    Retrievers,  and  how  to  Break  them.    By  Lieutenant- 

Colcnel  Sir  HKNRY  SMITH,  K.C.B.  With  an  Introduction  by  Mr  8.  E.  SHIRLEY, 
President  of  the  Kennel  Club.  Dedicated  by  special  permission  to  H.R.H.  thi 
Duke  of  Cornwall  and  York.  Crown  8vo,  5s. 

SNELL.     The   Fourteenth   Century.     "Periods   of    European 

Literature."    By  F.  J.  SNELL.    Crown  8vo,  5s.  net. 

"SON  OF  THE  MARSHES,  A." 

From  Spring  to  Fall:  or,  When  Life  Stirs.    By  "  A  SON  OF 

THE  MARSHES."    Cheap  Uniform  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  3d. 

Within  an  Hour  of  London  Town :  Among  Wild  Birds  and 

their  Haunts.    Edited  by  J.  A.  Owxu.    Cheap  Uniform  Edition.    Cr.  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

With  the  Woodlanders  and  by  the  Tide.     Cheap  Uniform 

Edition.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

On  Surrey  Hills.    Cheap  Uniform  Edition.   Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 
Annals  of  a  Fishing  Villaga    Cheap  Uniform  Edition.    Crown 

8vo,  Sa.  6d. 

SORLEY. 

The  Ethics  of  Naturalism.    By  W.  R  SORLEY,  Litt.D.,  L.L.D. 

Fellow  of  the  British  Academy,  Fellow  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge,  Professor 
of  Moral  Philosophy,  University  of  Cambridge.  Second  Edition.  Crown  8vo 
6*. 

Recent  Tendencies  in  Ethics.    Crown  8vo,  2s.  6d.  net 

SPROTT. 

The  Worship  and  Offices  of  the  Church  of  Scotland.     By 

GEORGE  W.  SPROTT,  D.D.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

The  Book  of  Common  Order  of  the  Church  of  Scotland,  com- 
monly known  as  John  Knox's  Liturgy.  With  Historical  Introduction  and  Illus- 
trative Notes.  Crown  8vo,  4s.  6d.  net. 

Scottish  Liturgies  of  the  Reign  of  James  VI.     Edited,  with 

an  Introduction  and  Notes.    Crown  8vo,  4s.  net. 

Euchologion :    A    Book    of    Common    Order.      Crown    8vo, 

4s.  6d.  net. 

STEEVENS. 

Things  Seen  :  Impressions  of  Men,  Cities,  and  Books.     By  the 

late  G.  W.  STEEVESS.  Edited  by  G.  8.  STREET.  With  a  Memoir  by  W.  E. 
HENLEY,  and  a  Photogravure  reproduction  of  Collier's  Portrait.  Memorial  Edi- 
tion. Crown  8vo,  6s. 


William  Black-wood  &  Sons.  29 


STEEVENS. 

From  Capetown  to  Lady  smith,  and  Egypt  in  1898.    Memorial 

Edition.    Crown  8vo,  6s.  p. 

In  India.    With  Map.    Memorial  Edition.     Crown  8vo,  6s. 
With    Kitchener  to    Khartum.      With   8  Maps  and   Plans. 

Memorial  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 

The  Land  of  the  Dollar.    Memorial  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 
Glimpses  of  Three  Nations.     Memorial  Edition.    Cr.  8vo,  6s. 
Monologues  of  the  Dead.   Memorial  Edition.  Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 
With  the  Conquering  Turk.  With  4  Maps.  Ch.  Ed.  Cr.  8vo,  6s. 

STEPHENS. 

The  Book  of  the  Farm  ;  detailing  the  Labours  of  the  Farmer, 

Farm-Steward,  Ploughman,  Shepherd,  Hedger,  Farm-Labourer,  Field-Worker, 
and  Cattle-man.  Illustrated  with  numerous  Portraits  of  Animals  and  Engravings 
of  Implements,  and  Plans  of  Farm  Buildings.  Fifth  Edition.  Revised,  and 
in  great  part  Re- written,  by  JAMBS  MAODONALD,  F.R.S.E.,  Secretary  Highland 
and  Agricultural  Society  of  Scotland.  Complete  in  Six  Divisional  Volumes, 
bound  in  cloth,  each  10s.  8d.,  or  handsomely  bound,  In  8  volumes  with  leather 
back  and  gilt  top,  £3,  3s. 

STEPHENS.     The  Eddy.     By    RICCAKDO   STEPHENS.     Crown 

8vo,  6s. 

STEWART.      Haud  Immemor.      Reminiscences   of    Legal    and 

Social  Life  in  Edinburgh  and  London,  1850-1900.  By  CHARLES  STEWART.  With 
10  Photogravure  Plates.  Royal  8vo,  7s.  6d. 

STEWART  AND  CUFF.    Practical  Nursing.    By  ISLA  STEWART, 

Matron  of  St  Bartholomew's  Hospital,  London ;  and  HERBERT  E.  CUFF,  M.D., 
F.R.C.S.,  Medical  Superintendent  North-Eastern  Fever  Hospital,  Tottenham, 
London.    With  Diagrams.     In  2   vols.   crown  8vo.    Vol.  I.     Second  Edition. 
3s.  6d.  net.    Vol.  II.,  3s.  6d.  net. 
Also  in  1  Volume,  5s.  net. 

STODDART.    John  Stuart  Blackie :   A  Biography.    By  ANNA 

M.  STODDART.    POPULAR  EDITION,  with  Portrait.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

STORMONTH. 

Dictionary  of  the  English  Language,  Pronouncing,  Etymo- 
logical, and  Explanatory.  By  the  Rev.  JAMES  STORMONTH.  Revised  by  the 
Rev.  P.  H.  PHELP.  Library  Edition.  New  and  Cheaper  Edition,  with  Supple- 
ment. Imperial  8vo,  handsomely  bound  in  half  morocco,  18s.  net. 

Etymological   and   Pronouncing  Dictionary   of    the  English 

Language.  Including  a  very  Copious  Selection  of  Scientific  Terms.  For  use  in 
Schools  and  Colleges,  and  as  a  Book  of  General  Reference.  The  Pronunciation 
carefully  revised  by  the  Rev.  P.  H.  PHELP,  M.A.  Cantab.  Sixteenth  Edition, 
Revised.  Crown  8vo,  pp.  1 000.  5s.  net. 

Handy  Dictionary.     New  Edition,  thoroughly  Revised.     By 

WILLIAM  BAYNK.    16mo,  Is. 

STORY.    William  Wetmore  Story  and  his  Friends.   From  Letters. 

Diaries,  and  Recollections.  By  HENRY  JAMES.  With  2  Portraits.  In  2  vols.  post 
8vo,  24s.  net 

STRAIN.    A  Prophet's  Reward.    By  E.  H.  STRAIN.    Crown  8vo, 


3O  William  Black-wood  &  Sons. 


SYNGE.     The  Story  of  the  World.     By  M.  B.  SYNGE.     With 

Coloured  Frontispieces  and  numerous  Illustrations  by  E.  M.  SYNGE,  A.R.E., 
and  Maps.    2  vols,  3s.  6d.  each  net. 


THEOBALD.    A  Text-Book  of  Agricultural  Zoology.    By  FEED. 

V.  THEOBALD.    With  numerous  Illustrations.    Crown  Svo,  8s.  6d. 

THOMSON.     Handy  Book  of  the  Flower-Garden.     By  DAVID 

THOMSON.     Crown  Svo,  5s. 

THOMSON.    A  Practical  Treatise  on  the  Cultivation  of  the 

Grape  Vine.    By  WILLIAM  THOMSON,  Tweed  Vineyards.    Tenth  Edition.    8vo,  5s. 

THOMSON.     History  of  the  Fife  Light  Horse.     By  Colonel 

ANSTKUTHER  THOMSON.    With  numerous  Portraits.    Small  4to,  21s.  net. 

THORBURN. 

The  Punjab  in  Peace  and  War.    By  S.  S.  THORBUKN.    Demy 

Svo.  12s.  6d.  net. 

India's  Saint  and  the  Viceroy.    A  Novel.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

THURSTON. 

The  Circle.    By  KATHERINE  CECIL  THTJRSTON.    Fifth  Impres- 
sion.   Crown  Svo,  6s. 

John  Chilcpte,  M.P.     Fourteenth  Impression,  crown  Svo,  6s. 

Cheap  Edition,  paper  cover,  tkl. 

The  Mystics.    With  Illustrations.     Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 
The  Fly  on  the  Wheel.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

TIELE.  Elements  of  the  Science  of  Religion.  Part  I.— Morpho- 
logical. Part  II. — Ontological.  Being  the  Gifford  Lectures  delivered  before  the 
University  of  Edinburgh  in  1896-98.  By  0.  P.  TIELE,  Theol.  D.,  Litt.D.  (Bonon. ), 
Hon.  M.R.A.8.,  &C-,  Professor  of  the  Science  of  Religion,  in  the  University  of 
Leiden.  In  3  vols.  post  Svo,  7s.  Ad.  net.  each. 

TRANSACTIONS  OF  THE  HIGHLAND  AND  AGRICUL- 
TURAL SOCIETY  OF  SCOTLAND.  Published  annually,  price  5a. 

TRAVERS. 

The  Way  of  Escape.    A  Novel.    By  GRAHAM  TRAVEKS  (Mar- 
garet Todd,  M.D.)    Second  Impression.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 

Mona  Maclean,  Medical  Student.    A  Novel.    Cheap  Edition, 

royal  Svo,  paper  cover,  6d. 

Windyhaugh.     Fourth  Edition.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 
Fellow  Travellers.    Fourth  Edition.    Crown  8vo,  6s. 


William  Blackwood  &  Sons.  31 


TRUSCOTT.    The  Marriage  of  Aminta.    By  L.  PARRY  TRUSCOTT. 

Crown  8vo,  6s. 

TULLOCH. 

Modern    Theories    in   Philosophy  and  Religion.      By  JOHN 

TtTLLOCH,  D.D.,  Principal  of  St  Mary's  College  in  the  University  of  8t 
Andrews,  and  one  of  her  Majesty's  Chaplains  in  Ordinary  in  Scotland. 
Svo.  15s. 

TURNER.      The  History  of  Local  Taxation  in  Scotland.      By 

STANLEY  HORSFALL  TURNER,  M.A.     Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

TWEEDIE.     The  Arabian   Horse:    His  Country  and   People. 

By  Major -General  W.  TWEEDIE,  C.8.I.,  Bengal  Staff  Corps;  for  many  years 
H.B.M.'s  Consul- General,  Baghdad,  and  Political  Resident  for  the  Government 
of  India  in  Turkish  Arabia.  In  one  vol.  royal  4to,  with  Seven  Coloured  Plate* 
and  other  Illustrations,  and  a  Map  of  the  Country.  Large  Paper  Edition.  Price 
£6,  6s.  net. 

VAUGHAN.   The  Romantic  Revolt.    By  Prof  essor  C.  E.  VAUGHAN. 

Crown  Svo,  5s.  net. 

VOYAGE  OF  THE  "SCOTIA,"  THE.    Being  the  Record  of 

a  Voyage  of  Exploration  in  Antartic  Seas.  By  THREE  OF  THE  STAFF.  Demy 
Svo,  21s.  net. 

WADDELL. 

Christianity  as  an  Ideal.    By  Rev.  P.  HATELY  WADDELL,  B.D. 

Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 

Essays  on  Faith.     Crown  Svo,  3s.  6d. 

WARREN'S  (SAMUEL)  WORKS  :- 

Diary  of  a  Late  Physician.     Cloth,  2s.  6d. ;  boards,  2s. ;  paper 

cover,  Is. 

Now  and  Then.     The  Lily  and  the  Bee.      Intellectual  and 

Moral  Development  of  the  Present  Age.    4s.  6d. 

Essays  :  Critical,  Imaginative,  and  Juridical.     5s. 
WATSON.    The  Skipper.    By  GILBERT  WATSON.    Crown  Svo,  6s. 
WATT.     By  Still  Waters.     By  MACLEAN   WATT.     Is.  6d.  net. 

Leather,  2s.  net. 

WENLEY.     Aspects  of  Pessimism.     By  R.  M.  WENLEY,  M.A., 

D.Sc.,  D.Phil.,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Michigan,  U.S.A. 
Crown  Svo,  6s. 

WHIBLEY. 

Thackeray.       "Modern    English    Writers."       By    CHARLES 

.WHIBLEY.     Crown  Svo,  2s.  6d. 

William  Pitt.     With  Portraits  and  Caricatures.     Crown  Svo, 

6s.  net. 

American  Sketches.     Crown  Svo,  6s. 


32  William  Blackivood  &  Sons. 

WILLIAMSON.    Ideals  of  Ministry.    By  A.  WALLACE  WILLIAM- 
SON, D.D.,  St  Cuthbert's,  Edinburgh.    Crown  8vo,  3s.  6d. 

WILSON.    The  Prophets  and  Prophecy  to  the  Close  of  the  Eighth 

Century  B.C.  By  the  Rev.  ALEXANDER  WILSON,  M.A.,  Minister  of  Ythan  Wells, 
Aberdeenshire.  With  Introductory  Preface  by  the  Rev.  ALLAN  MENZIES,  D.D., 
Professor  of  Biblical  Criticism  in  the  University  of  St  Andrews.  Fcap.  8vo,  Is. 
net. 

WILSON. 

Works  of  Professor  Wilson.      Edited  by  his    Son -in -Law, 

Professor  FERRIKR.    12  Tola,  crown  8vo,  £2,  8s. 

Christopher  in  his  Sporting-Jacket.     2  vols.,  8s. 

Isle  of  Palms,  City  of  the  Plague,  and  other  Poems.    4s. 

Lights  and  Shadows  of  Scottish  Life,  and  other  Tales.   4s. 

Essays,  Critical  and  Imaginative.     4  vols.,  16s. 

The  Noctes  Ambrosianse.    4  vols.,  16s. 

Homer  and  his  Translators,  and  the  Greek  Drama.     Crown 

8VO,  48. 

WORSLEY. 

Homer's  Odyssey.      Translated  into  English  Verse  in  the 

Spenserian  Stanza.  By  PHILIP  STANHOPK  WORSLEY,  11. A.  New  and  Cheaper 
Edition.  Post  8vo,  7s.  6d.  net. 

Homer's  Iliad.    Translated  by  P.  S.  Worsley  and  Prof.  Con- 

Ington.    8  vols.  crown  Svo,  21s. 

WOTHERSPOON. 

Kyrie  Eleison  ("Lord,  have  Mercy").    A  Manual  of  Private 

Prayers.  With  Notes  and  Additional  Matter.  By  H.  J.  WOTHERSPOON,  M.A., 
of  St  Oswald's,  Edinburgh.  Cloth,  red  edges,  Is.  net ;  limp  leather,  Is.  6d.  net. 

Before  and  After.    Being  Part  I.  of  'Kyrie  Eleison.'    Cloth, 

limp,  6d.  net. 

The  Second  Prayer  Book  of  King  Edward  the  Sixth  (1552)  along 

with  the  Liturgy  of  Compromise,  edited  by  Rev.  G.  W.  SPROTT,  D.D.  Crown 
Svo,  4s.  net. 


6/08 


University  of  California 

SOUTHERN  REGIONAL  LIBRARY  FACILITY 

405  Hilgard  Avenue,  Los  Angeles,  CA  90024-1388 

Return  this  material  to  the  library 

from  which  it  was  borrowed.