Skip to main content

Full text of "Hobbes"

See other formats


UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA 


LIBRARY 

OF  THE 

UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA. 


Class 


A 
*   , 


ENGLISH   MEN   OF   LETTERS 


HOBBES 


BY 


SIR    LESLIE    STEPHEN 


;  UNIVERSITY 


gotfe 
THE   MACMILLAN    COMPANY 

LONDON:  MACMILLAN  &  CO.,  LTD. 
1904 

All  rights  reserved 


COPYRIGHT,  1904, 
BY  THE  MACMILLAN  COMPANY. 


Set  up  and  electrotyped.      Published  July,  1904. 


Nortooott 

J.  S.  Cashing  &  Co.  —  Berwick  &  Smith  Co. 
Norwood,  Mass.,  U.S.A. 


CONTENTS 


CHAPTER  I 

PAGE 

LIFE   ......••••• 


CHAPTER   II 
THE  WORLD 70 

CHAPTER   III 
MAN 114 

CHAPTER  IV 
THE  STATE 173 

INDEX  .........     239 


HOBBES 

CHAPTER   I 

LIFE 

THE  biographer  of  the  present  day  knows  not  whether 
to  envy  or  to  pity  his  predecessors  in  the  seventeenth 
century.  The  increased  advantages  bring  responsi- 
bilities. The  materials  available  were  formerly  of 
manageable  bulk ;  nor  was  it  thought  necessary  to 
emulate  scientific  procedure  by  minutely  investigating 
a  man's  "  environment "  and  tracing  all  the  influences 
which  moulded  his  character  or  the  character  of  his 
ancestors.  Thomas  Hobbes,  of  Malmesbury,  author 
of  the  Leviathan,  was  the  most  conspicuous  English 
thinker  in  the  whole  period  between  Bacon  and  Locke, 
and  his  long  career,  described  on  the  modern  scale, 
would  certainly  have  filled  at  least  a  couple  of  portly 
volumes.  The  actual  accounts  fill  only  a  few  pages. 
They  tantalise  the  reader  by  many  glimpses  of  a  very 
interesting  personality.  Yet,  brief  as  they  are,  they 
give  perhaps  as  distinct  an  impression  of  the  main 
outlines  of  a  notable  figure  as  could  have  been  pro- 
duced by  far  more  elaborate  detail. 

Hobbes  himself  was  obviously  convinced  —  I  have 
reasons  for  hoping  that  his  conviction  was  well  founded 

B  I 


2  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

—  that  a  distant  posterity  would  thirst  for  information 
about  him.  At  the  age  of  eighty-four  he  wrote  an 
autobiography  in  Latin  elegiacs.  Two  years  later 
Anthony  Wood  published  his  book  upon  the  history 
and  antiquities  of  the  University  of  Oxford.  Through 
John  Aubrey,  their  common  friend,  he  obtained  for 
it  an  autobiographical  notice  from  Hobbes.  Unluckily 
Dr.  Fell,  Dean  of  Christchurch,  who  bore  the  expense 
of  publishing,  claimed  also  the  right  of  editing  the 
work.  Hobbes's  statement  that  he  had  spent  a  certain 
period  in  scribendo  librum,  qui  nunc  non  soltim  in  Anglia 
sed  in  vicinis  gentibus  notissimus  est  nomine  Leviathan 
was  amended  by  inserting  monstrosissimum  after  librum, 
and  jmblico  damno  before  notissimus.  Hobbes  was  in- 
formed of  this  and  other  changes  in  the  same  spirit, 
and  printed  a  remonstrance.  Fell  replied  (what  it  was 
hardly  for  him  to  say)  that  an  old  man,  with  one  foot 
in  the  grave,  ought  not  to  trouble  himself  and  the 
world  about  such  trifles,  and  printed  at  the  end  of 
the  book  a  contemptuous  reply  to  irritabile  illud  et  va- 
nissimum  animal  Malmesburiense.  The  original  auto- 
biography fortunately  remains ;  it  was  printed  soon 
after  Hobbes's  death  along  with  the  poem,  and  a  Vitce 
Hobbiance  Auctarium  (by  a  Dr.  Blackbourne)  contain- 
ing some  further  information.  The  Auctarium  was 
founded  upon  the  collections  of  Aubrey,  made  for  the 
benefit  of  Wood's  later  book  the  Athence  Oxonienses. 
Aubrey  was  a  personal  friend  of  Hobbes,  who  came 
from  the  same  county,  and  did  his  best  to  anticipate 
Boswell,  though  his  aspirations  fell  far  short  of  such 
success.1  From  these  and  sundry  incidental  refer- 

1  Aubrey's  Brief  Lives,  containing  these  notes,  have  been  care- 
fully editr- '  by  Mr.  Andrew  Clarke.     18(J8. 


i.]  LIFE  3 

ences,  we  derive  such  knowledge  of  Hobbes  as  we 
possess ;  and  in  his  case,  as  decidedly  as  in  that  of  any 
philosopher,  a  knowledge  of  the  man  is  very  important 
to  a  fair  appreciation  of  the  work. 

In  the  year  1588  a  Thomas  Hobbes  was  vicar  of 
Westport,  adjoining  Malmesbury,  and  of  the  neigh- 
bouring parish  of  Charlton.  He  married,  we  are  told, 
".  .  .  Middleton  of  Brokinborough  (a  yeomanly  fam- 
ily) "  :  but  with  that  information  students  of  heredity 
must  be  content.  The  vicar  was  "  one  of  the  ignorant 
Sir  Johns  of  Queen  Elizabeth's  time :  could  only  read 
the  prayers  of  the  Church  and  the  homilies,  and  dis- 
esteeined  learning  as  not  knowing  the  sweetness  of 
it."  Another  anecdote  declares  that  he  was  a  "good 
fellow,"  and  that  after  playing  cards  all  Saturday 
night,  he  went  to  sleep  in  church,  and  in  his  dreams 
announced  to  the  congregation  that  clubs  were 
trumps.  Mrs.  Hobbes  heard  rumours  of  the  Spanish 
Armada,  and  apparently  thought  that  Malmesbury 
would  be  the  natural  "  objective >;  of  an  invading 
force.  The  result  was  the  premature  birth  of  her  son 
Thomas,  early  in  the  morning  of  the  5th  of  April 
1588.  According  to  Aubrey  the  time  was  well  chosen, 
as  the  child's  horoscope,  like  that  of  Oliver  Cromwell/ 
indicated  future  eminence.  Hobbes  himself  says  that 
he  and  terror  were  born  twins.  Characteristically  he 
speaks  of  his  timidity  with  a  certain  complacency,  and 
to  it  he  attributes  his  hatred  of  his  country's  foes  and 
his  love  of  peace,  with  the  muses  and  friendly  com- 
pany. Not  long  after  his  birth  his  father,  "  a  choleric 
man,"  was  provoked  on  purpose  at  the  church  door  by 
"a  parson  (which,  I  think,  succeeded  him  at  West- 
port)."  So  Hobbes  the  elder  struck  him  ^nd  was 


4  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

forced  to  fly  for  it.  He  retired  to  a  vague  region 
"  beyond  London,"  and  there  disappears  from  history. 
Mrs.  Hobbes  was  left  at  Malmesbury  with  three 
children,  including  John,  Thomas's  senior  by  two 
years,  and  a  daughter.  Fortunately  a  childless  uncle, 
Francis  Hobbes,  glover  and  alderman  of  Malmesbury, 
took  charge  of  the  deserted  family.  Thomas  was  sent 
to  school  at  Westport  church  at  the  age  of  four,  where 
he  learnt  reading  and  arithmetic.  Thence  he  passed 
to  a  school  in  Malmesbury,  and  afterwards  to  one  kept 
by  a  Mr.  Latimer,  "  a  good  Grecian,  and  the  first  that 
came  into  our  parts  hereabout  since  the  Reformation." 
Latimer  delighted  in  his  scholar,  and  used  to  teach  him 
with  "  two  or  three  ingeniose  youths  more  "  till  nine 
in  the  evening.  Under  this  excellent  master,  Hobbes 
worked  to  such  good  purpose  that  at  the  age  of  four- 
teen he  had  translated  the  Medea  of  Euripides  into 
Latin  iambics.  He  was  "  playsome  enough,"  though 
he  had  even  then  a  "  contemplative  melancholinesse  "  : 
and  he  was  nicknamed  "  the  crow  "  on  account  of  his 
black  hair. 

The  promise  which  he  had  shown  induced  his  uncle 
to  send  him  to  Magdalen  Hall  at  Oxford.  He 
apparently  began  residence  in  the  beginning  of  1603 
(when  he  would  be  just  fifteen)  but  was  not  admitted 
to  his  B.A.  degree  till  February  1608.  At  Oxford  he 
can  scarcely  have  fulfilled  his  uncle's  expectations. 
He  was  one  of  the  many  eminent  men  who  acknow- 
ledge but  a  small  debt  of  gratitude  to  their  university. 
Long  afterwards  (in  his  Behemoth)  Hobbes  intimates 
that  the  parliamentary  commissioners,  for  whom  he 
had  otherwise  little  enough  affection,  did  some  good 
by  purging  the  university  of  men  morally  unworthy, 


i.]  LITE  5 

as  well  as  of  those  opposed  to  them  in  theology. 
Many  parents,  he  says,  had  reason  to  complain  that 
their  sons  were  allowed  to  fall  into  vicious  practices, 
and  taught  by  incompetent  tutors  little  older  than 
themselves.  The  discipline  and  the  studies  at  the 
Oxford  of  that  period  seem,  in  fact,  to  have  been  in 
much  need  of  reform.  Hobbes,  however,  writing  in 
his  old  age,  had  other  causes  of  quarrel  with  the 
universities,  which  he  had  come  to  regard  as  the 
strongholds  of  obscurantism ;  and  it  does  not  appear 
that,  while  himself  a  student,  his  eyes  had  been  open 
to  the  evils  which  he  afterwards  recognised. 

Magdalen  Hall  was,  during  the  early  part  of  the 
century,  the  favourite  resort  of  the  Puritans.  But 
there  is  no  symptom  that  Hobbes  was  at  the  time 
either  attracted  or  repelled  by  the  religious  views  of 
his  teachers.  His  account  of  his  studies  suggests  the 
probable  state  of  the  case.  He  was  admitted,  he  says, 
to  the  class  of  logic,  and  listened  eagerly  to  the  dis- 
course of  his  beardless  teacher.  He  was  put  through 
the  regular  Barbara  celarent,  learnt  the  rules  slowly, 
and  then  cast  them  aside,  and  was  permitted  to  prove 
things  after  his  own  fashion.  Swift,  long  afterwards, 
speaks  in  much  the  same  way  of  his  logical  studies 
in  Dublin.  Then  he  was  taught  physics ;  the  tutor 
explained  that  all  things  were  composed  of  matter 
and  form;  that  "species,"  flying  through  the  air, 
impressed  the  eye  and  ear;  and  attributed  much  to 
sympathy  and  antipathy.  Hobbes  found  such  things 
above  his  understanding ;  but  it  did  not  apparently 
occur  to  him  till  a  later  period  that  they  were  unintel- 
ligible because  nonsensical.  Like  many  other  lads,  in 
fact,  he  found  his  lessons  tiresome ;  and  he  returned  to 


6  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

reading  the  books  of  which  he  had  already  an  im- 
perfect knowledge.  He  took  a  particular  pleasure  in 
maps  of  the  world  and  the  stars ;  he  liked  to  follow 
the  sun  in  fancy,  and  to  trace  the  voyages  of  the  great 
circumnavigators,  Drake  and  Cavendish.  "  He  tooke 
great  delight"  as  Aubrey  says,  "to  goe  to  the  book- 
binders' shops  and  lie  gaping  on  mappes " ;  but  it 
does  not  appear  that  the  records  of  the  Elizabethan 
sailors  inspired  him  with  the  usual  boyish  ambition 
of  running  away  to  sea.  Aubrey  records  one  other 
amusement.  Hobbes  told  him,  in  order  to  prove  the 
sharp-sightedness  of  jackdaws,  how  he  used  to  tie 
"  leaden-counters J;  with  pack-thread,  smeared  with 
bird-lime  and  baited  with  cheese  parings.  The  jack- 
daws would  "  spy  them  at  a  vast  distance  up  in  the  aire 
and  as  far  as  Osney  Abbey  "  and  strike  at  the  "  baite." 
Athletic  sports  had  not  yet  organised  idleness,  but 
Hobbes  seems  to  have  found  sufficient  excuses  for  not 
attending  lectures.  The  results  of  his  university 
career  were  so  far  negative ;  but  an  incident  which 
happened  soon  after  his  degree,  seems  to  show  that 
the  authorities  thought  well  of  him :  well  enough,  at 
least  —  for  such  inferences  are  not  always  very  safe  — 
to  declare  him  fit  to  be  employed  by  somebody  else. 
The  principal  of  Magdalen  Hall  recommended  him  to 
William  Cavendish,  afterwards  first  Earl  of  Devon- 
shire, and  Hobbes  formed  a  connection  with  the 
Cavendish  family  which  was  of  vital  importance  to 
his  whole  career. 

The  first  conspicuous  Cavendish,  the  Sir  William 
who  was  employed  in  the  visitation  of  monasteries  by 
Henry  VIII.,  and  had  certain  pickings  from  their 
estates,  married  Elizabeth,  a  rich  heiress  in  Derby- 


i.]  LIFE  7 

shire,  generally  known  as  "  Bess  of  Hardwick."  She 
was  an  imperious  lady,  who  induced  her  husband  to 
settle  in  Derbyshire,  where  she  built  great  houses  at 
Hardwick  and  Chatsworth.  She  had  determined,  it 
seems,  not  to  die  as  long  as  she  could  build ;  and  it 
was  only  a  hard  frost,  suspending  her  building  opera- 
tions, which  induced  her  to  leave  the  world  in  1608  at 
the  age  of  ninety.  She  had  before  that  time  married 
two  other  husbands,  the  last  being  the  Earl  of  Shrews- 
bury, the  host  or  gaoler  of  Mary  Queen  of  Scots.  All 
her  fortune,  however,  went  to  her  second  son,  William 
Cavendish,  who  also  inherited  at  a  later  period  the 
estates  of  his  elder  brother,  and  was  thus  one  of  the 
richest  men  in  England.  In  1618  he  became  first 
Earl  of  Devonshire,  having  bought  the  title  for  £10,000 
from  James  I.  In  1608,  when  Hobbes  was  leaving 
Oxford,  he  was  father  of  a  son  William,  afterwards 
second  earl,  two  years  younger  than  Hobbes.  Ac- 
cording to  Aubrey,  the  younger  William  (possibly  his 
father),  "had  a  conceit  that  he  should  profit  more  in 
learning  if  he  had  a  scholar  of  his  own  age  to  wait  on 
him  than  if  he  had  the  information  of  a  grave  doctor." 
Hobbes  became  "his  lordship's  page,  and  rode  a  hunt- 
ing and  hawking  with  him  and  kept  his  privy  purse." 
The  "  learning  "  seems  to  have  been  neglected :  Hobbes 
almost  forgot  his  Latin;  but  bought  a  few  books, 
especially  a  Caasar,  which  he  carried  in  his  pocket  and 
read  in  the  lobby  "while  his  lord  was  making  his 
visits."  Another  note  gives  a  rather  unpleasant  aspect 
of  Hobbes's  first  position.  "His  lord,"  says  Aubrey, 
"  who  was  a  waster,  sent  him  up  and  down  to  borrow 
money  and  to  get  gentlemen  to  be  bound  for  him, 
being  ashamed  to  speak  himself."  Hobbes,  we  are 


8  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

told,  "  took  cold,  being  wet  in  his  feet  (then  were  no 
hackney  coaches  to  stand  in  the  streets),  and  trod  both 
his  shoes  aside  the  same  way '  (whatever  that  may 
indicate).  Notwithstanding,  adds  Aubrey,  he  was 
loved  for  his  facetiousness  and  good-nature.  Young 
Cavendish  had  been  married  to  Christiana,  daughter  of 
Edward,  Lord  Bruce  of  Kinross.  James  L,  who  had 
been  served  by  Lord  Bruce  in  the  negotiations  with 
Cecil  which  secured  his  accession  to  the  throne,  gave 
the  bride  £5000.  She  was  only  twelve  years  and 
three  months  old  at  her  marriage,  and  the  bridegroom, 
who  was  eighteen,  was,  for  the  present,  more  in  need 
of  a  tutor  than  a  wife. 

In  1610  the  two  young  men  made  the  grand  tour, 
visiting  France  and  Italy.  No  record  of  their  adven- 
tures is  preserved,  but  Hobbes  says  that  he  brought 
back  some  knowledge,  both  of  the  modern  languages 
and  of  men  and  manners  in  the  countries  visited.  It 
was  the  year  in  which  Henry  IV.  fell  by  the  knife 
of  Ravaillac  ;  Hobbes  mentions  the  murder  once  or 
twice  in  his  works  ;  but  it  was  so  apt  an  illustration 
of  his  view  as  to  the  relation  between  kings  and  priests 
that  no  personal  memory  need  be  implied.  He  brought 
back  one  lesson  of  importance.  He  discovered  that 
the  scholastic  doctrine,  of  which  he  had  acquired  a 
smattering  at  Oxford,  was  everywhere  treated  with 
contempt  by  the  intelligent,  and  was  passing  out  of 
fashion.  He  continued  to  live  with  the  pupil  who 
had  now  become  a  friend.  For  the  next  eighteen  years 
Hobbes  was  a  member  of  the  Cavendish  family.  These 
years,  he  says,  were  by  far  the  pleasantest  of  his  life, 
and  still  (that  is  when  he  was  eighty-four)  revisited 
him  in  his  dreams.  His  patron  allowed  him  leisure 


i.]  LIFE  9 

and   provided  him  with  books  of  all  kinds  for  his 
studies.     There  was  no  one,  says  Hobbes,  in  whose 
house  a  man  would  less  need  a  university.     Having 
thrown  aside  his  philosophy,  Hobbes  began  by  rubbing 
up  his  old  classical  knowledge.     He  read  poets  and 
historians  with  the  comments  of  grammarians,  in  order 
to  acquire  the  art  of  writing  a  clear  Latin  style,  then 
a  matter  of  practical  importance  for  a  man  of  letters. 
He  does  not  mention  another  study  which   occupied 
part  of  the  time.     Aubrey  tells  us  that  he  repented 
of  having  spent  two  years  in  reading  romances  and 
plays,   and  often  lamented   this  waste   of   time.      It 
might,  as  Aubrey  suggests,  "  furnish  him  with  copie 
of    words."      Anyhow,    he    undertook    another    task 
which,  one  can  well  believe,  helped  him  to  acquire 
the  clear  and  forcible  style  of  his  English  writings. 
This  was  his  translation  of  Thucydides.     He  said 
long  after  that  he  had  learnt  from.  Thucydides  how 
much  wiser  one   man  is   than  a   body  of  men,  and 
meant    to    warn    his    countrymen    against    trusting 
popular   orators.       It    must    be    admitted    that    this 
method   of    meeting    democratic   tendencies   was   de- 
cidedly roundabout.      Few  people  could  be  expected 
to  read  the  translated  book,  and  those  who  did,  might 
fail  to  draw  the  desired  inference.     Hobbes  was  pro- 
bably crediting  himself  with  intentions  suggested  by 
later  experience.     The  introductory  remarks  show  his 
admiration  for  the  skill  with  which  Thucydides  has 
made   his   narrative   pregnant  with  wisdom   without/ 
digressing   into   lectures.      He  ridicules    the  ancient 
critic  who  assumed  that  the  "  scope  of  history  "  should 
be  "not  profit  by  writing  truth,  but  delight  of  the 
hearer  as  if  it  were  a  sonff."      He  could  not  have 


10  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

offered  better  advice  to  some  modern  historians. 
Hobbes,  we  may  suppose,  was  not  very  much  im- 
pressed by  the  weighty  political  utterances  of  the 
great  historian,  but  felt  a  certain  congeniality  to  his 
own  intellectual  tendencies.  Anyhow  the  attempt  to 
straighten  out  Thucydides'  tough  sentences  into  clear 
English  was  as  good  practice  as  could  be  desired. 
Hobbes  had  not  received  such  training  as  is  generally 
requisite  for  fine  scholarship,  and  Jowett,  in  his 
preface  to  his  own  version,  says  that  his  predecessor's 
work  is  very  rough  and  inaccurate,  and  has  been 
praised  beyond  its  merits.  I  cannot  dispute  the 
verdict  of  so  high  an  authority.  My  readers  may 
judge  from  a  short  specimen.  It  is  part  of  the  passage 
containing  Thucydides'  reflections  upon  the  seditions 
in  Corey ra.  They  would  have  a  special  interest  for  the 
author  of  the  Leviathan. 

,.$  "  And  many  and  heinous  things  happened  in  the 
cities  through  this  sedition,  which  though  they  have 
been  before,  and  shall  be  ever  as  long  as  human  nature 
is  the  same,  yet  they  are  more  calm  and  of  different 
kinds  according  to  the  several  conjunctures.  For  in 
peace  and  prosperity  as  well  cities  as  private  men  are 
better  minded  because  they  be  not  plunged  into 
necessity  of  doing  anything  against  their  will.  But 
war,  taking  away  the  affluence  of  daily  necessaries,  is 
a  most  violent  master,  and  conformeth  most  men's 
passions  to  the  present  occasion.  The  cities  therefore 
being  now  in  sedition,  and  those  that  fell  into  it  later 
having  heard  what  had  been  done  in  the  former,  they 
far  exceeded  the  same  in  newness  of  conceit  both 
for  the  art  of  assailing,  and  for  the  strangeness  of 
their  revenges.  The  received  value  of  names  iin- 


i.]  LIFE  11 

posed  for  signification  of  things  was  changed  into 
arbitrary.  For  inconsiderate  boldness  was  counted 
true-hearted  manliness ;  provident  deliberation  a 
handsome  fear ;  modesty,  the  cloak  of  cowardice ;  to 
be  wise  in  everything,  to  be  lazy  in  everything.  A 
furious  suddenness  was  reputed  a  point  of  valour.  To 
readvise  for  the  better  security  was  held  for  a  fail- 
pretext  of  tergiversation.  He  that  was  fierce  was 
always  trusty ;  and  he  that  contraried  such  a  one  was 
suspected.  He  that  did  insidiate,  if  it  took,  was  a 
wise  man ;  but  he  that  could  smell  out  a  trap  laid,  a 
more  dangerous  man  than  he.  But  he  that  had  been 
so  provident  as  not  to  need  to  do  the  one  or  the  other, 
was  said  to  be  a  dissolver  of  society,  and  one  that 
stood  in  fear  of  his  adversary.  In  brief,  he  that 
could  outstrip  another  in  the  doing  of  an  evil  act,  or 
that  could  persuade  another  thereto  that  never  meant 
it,  was  commended." 

Such  are  the  evils,  Hobbes  would  have  said,  which 
follow  when  men's  passions  are  let  loose  by  the 
destruction  or  dislocation  of  a  settled  sovereign 
authority.  He  did  not,  however,  at  present  set  forth 
his  own  views,  and  the  translation  remained  for  some 
time  unpublished.  The  years  that  he  passed  with  the 
Cavendishes,  the  years  so  fondly  remembered,  must 
have  been  in  the  main  devoted  to  thinking  and  read- 
ing in  the  intervals  of  the  duties,  whatever  precisely 
they  may  have  been,  imposed  upon  him  by  his  relation 
to  his  patron.  His  position  enabled  him  to  make 
acquaintance  with  some  of  the  most  famous  men  of 
the  day.  When  Aubrey  first  met  him  a  few  years, 
later  (1634),  his  talk  ran  a  good  deal  upon  Ben  Jonson' 
and  Sir  Robert  Ay  ton.  Jonson,  of  course,  was  then! 


12  HOBBES  [CHAP, 

the  most  far  shining  of  literary  lights  ;  and  though 

4  A^ton,  who  was  related  to  the  wife  of  Hobbes's  patron, 
has  fallen  into  obscurity,  he  was  then  regarded  as 
an  eminent  critic  and  poet.  Hobbes  submitted  his 
Thucydides  to  these  two.  A  much  more  interesting 

1  connection  was  that  with  Bacon.  Aubrey  tells  some 
anecdotes  which  suggest  certain  chronological  diffi- 
culties. Bacon,  he  says,  "used  to  contemplate  in  his 
delicious  walks  at  Gorhambury."  When  a  notion 
darted  into  his  mind,  he  would  have  it  set  down  by 
one  of  his  attendants,  and  he  often  said  that  Hobbes 
was  qiiicker  than  any  one  else  at  catching  his  meaning 
and  putting  it  down  intelligibly.  Aubrey  says  also 
that  Hobbes  helped  to  translate  some  of  Bacon's 
essays,  notably  that  upon  the  greatness  of  cities,  into 

\  Latin  :  the  Latin  translation  was  published  posthu- 
mously in  1636.  Hobbes,  too,  is  Aubrey's  authority 
for  the  familiar  story  of  Bacon's  death  being  caused  by 
the  experiment  of  stuffing  a  fowl  with  snow.  Bacon 
knew  something  of  Hobbes's  patron,  and  there  is 
nothing  improbable  in  the  other  statements.  The 
time  at  which  the  meetings  took  place  was  probably 
between  Bacon's  loss  of  office  in  1621  and  his  death  in 
1626.  The  amount  of  intercourse  must  be  doubtful. 
One  point  however  is  clear.  Bacon  and  Hobbes 

v  were  alike  in  rejecting  the  old  scholasticism,  and  in 
being  profoundly  impressed  by  the  early  stages  of  the 
modern  scientific  movement.  But  in  other  respects 
the  relation  is  one  of  contrast.  Bacon's  great  aim  was 
o  extend  the  physical  sciences  by  systematising  ex- 
perimental methods.  Hobbes,  though  he  incidentally 
notices  one  of  Bacon's  experiments,  has,  as  Groom 
Robertson  put  it,  "  nothing  but  scorn  for  experiment 


i.]  LIFE  13 

in  physics."  His  own  method  is  essentially  deductive, 
and  he  takes  no  notice  of  what  is  called  "  Baconian 
induction."  Hobbes's  political  theories  have  no  exact 
counterpart  in  Bacon.  Bacon  embodied  in  his  various 
writings  much  statesmanlike  reflection,  showing  the 
deep  insight  of  a  keen  observer  profoundly  interested 
in  the  affairs  of  the  day.  Hobbes,  as  we  shall  see, 
also  watched  the  political  movement  of  the  time,  but/ 
as  an  outside  spectator ;  and  he  constructs  an  abstract 

^/" 

theory  as  dogmatically  as  his  successor  and,  in  some 
degree,  his  disciple,  Eousseau.  The  contrast  of  style 
was  well  put  by  Sprat,  in  answer  to  Sorbiere.  who  had 
mentioned  the  personal  relation,  and  inferred  an  intel- 
lectual affinity.  "  Bacon,"  he  says,  "  is  short,  allusive, 
and  abounding  in  metaphors  :  Hobbes,  round,  close, 
sparing  of  similitudes,  but  ever  extraordinarily  decent 
in  them.  The  one's  way  of  reasoning  proceeds  on 
particulars  and  pleasant  images,  only  suggesting 
new  ways  of  experimenting  without  any  pretence 
to  the  mathematics.  The  other  is  bold,  resolved, 
settled  upon  general  conclusions,  and  in  them  (if 
we  will  believe  his  friend)  dogmatical."  Hobbes 
may  doubtless  have  received  from  his  intercourse 
with  Bacon  some  impulse  towards  his  philosophical 
enterprise,  but  as  yet  there  is  no  proof  of  his  having 
undertaken  to  be  a  philosopher  at  this  early  moment 
in  his  career,  and  the  impulse,  when  it  came,  was 
derived  from  other  sources.  Other  friendships,  which 
I  shall  have  to  mention,  may  have  begun  at  this 
period ;  but  for  the  present  Hobbes  had  made  no 
attempt  to  impress  the  world,  and  would  only  be 
known  to  others  than  his  immediate  friends,  as  the 
secretary  of  the  Earl  of  Devonshire. 


14  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

In  1626,  on  the  death  of  the  first  earl,  Hobbes's 
patron  succeeded  to  the  peerage,  but  died  in  June  1628. 
During  the  interval  Hobbes  wrote  a  Latin  poem, 
giving  an  account  of  a  short  tour  in  the  Peak,  made  in 
company  with  the  second  earl.  It  was,  it  appears,  a 
new  year's  gift  to  his  friend,  who  rewarded  him  with 
a  present  of  £5.  The  De^Mlrabilibus^Pecci  Carmen 
begins  with  a  description  of  the  beauties  of  Chatsworth, 
and  the  early  landscape-gardening  of  "  Bess  of  Hard- 
wick,"  where  "art,  dissimulating  art,"  has  produced 
sham  rocks  and  streams  and  fountains.  Then  he 
describes  the  ride,  in  the  course  of  which  he  and  his 
companion  see  the  seven  wonders  of  the  Peak :  Chats- 
worth  itself,  the  cave  called  after  the  devil,  Mam  Tor, 
Elden  Hole,  the  hot  spring,  Pool's  Cavern,  and  Buxton 
Well.  Hobbes,  it  is  needless  to  say,  does  not  antici- 
y  pate  the  Wordsworthian  cult  of  Nature ;  but  he  is 
a  very  good  specimen  of  the  early  sightseer.  Elden 
Hole,  it  seems,  was  already  famous  in  the  days  of  Queen 
Elizabeth.  The  Earl  of  Leicester  of  that  time  caused 
a  man  to  be  let  down  into  it  hanging  to  a  rope,  and 
then  to  drop  stones  to  estimate  the  remaining  depth. 
When  drawn  up  again  he  was  too  horror-struck  to 
speak  intelligibly,  was  seized  with  a  frenzy,  and  died 
in  a  week.  I  regret  to  see  that  recent  explorers  have 
not  spared  the  romance  even  of  Elden  Hole.  It  is 
only  two  hundred  feet  deep,  with  an  inner  cave  of  less 
than  a  hundred.  The  party  slept  at  Buxton,  where 
they  had  two  baths  and  a  very  poor  supper  (such 
descriptions  are  an  essential  part  of  all  mountaineering 
literature),  and  returned  next  day  to  Chatsworth. 
The  excursion  was,  we  may  guess,  one  of  the  incidents 
which  revisited  Hobbes  in  the  dreams  of  his  old  age. 


i.]  LIFE  15 

Unfortunately  the  poet,  while  describing  the  wonders, 
does  not  condescend  to  report  the  conversation  of  the 
travellers.1 

The  death  of  the  second  earl  had  serious  effects  for 
Hobbes.  In  the  "  Epistle  Dedicatory  "  prefixed  to  the 
Thucydidas.  Hobbes  tells  the  young  heir  that  he  is 
bound  to  dedicate  his  labour  to  "  rny  master  now  in 
heaven."  The  panegyric  upon  the  dead  man  which 
naturally  follows  is  honourably  free  from  the  exces- 
sive adulation  of  such  documents.  Hobbes's  sincerity 
is  unmistakable.  He  speaks  of  the  earl's  liberality  to 
himself,  his  good  sense  and  freedom  from  factious 
motives.  He  gave  sound  advice  and  was  "  one  whom 
no  man  was  able  to  draw  or  jus  tie  out  of  the  straight 
path  of  justice.  Of  which  virtue,  I  know  not  whether 
he  deserved  more  by  his  severity  in  imposing  it  (as  he 
did  to  his  last  breath)  on  himself,  or  by  his  magna- 
nimity in  not  exacting  it  to  himself  from  others.  No 
man  better  discerned  of  men :  and  therefore  was  he 
constant  in  his  friendships,  because  he  regarded  not 
the  fortune  nor  the  adherence  but  the  men,  with  whom 
also  he  conversed  with  an  openness  of  heart  that  had 
no  other  guard  than  his  own  integrity  and  that  nil 
conscire.  To  his  equals  he  carried  himself  equally,  and 
to  his  inferiors  familiarly  ;  but  maintaining  his  respect 

1  De  Quincey  in  his  Essay  upon  Murder  as  one  of  the  Fine 
Arts,  quotes  from  an  anonymous  tract  of  1670  ("  The  creed  of 
Mr.  Hobbes  examined  "),  by  Thomas  Tenisou,  afterwards 
archbishop.  It  describes  a  meeting  with  Hobbes  at  Buxton,  to 
which  place  Hobbes's  poem  had  attracted  the  author.  Hobbes 
has  a  long  dialogue  with  a  student  of  divinity,  and  is 
thoroughly  confuted.  Tenison  however  states  that  the  intro- 
ductory circumstances  as  well  as  the  dialogue  are  purely 
fictitious. 


16  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

fully  and  only  with  the  native  splendour  of  his  birth. 
In  sum,  he  was  one  in  whom  it  might  plainly  be  per- 
ceived that  honour  and  honesty  are  but  the  same  thing 
in  different  degrees  of  persons."  The  earl  had  shown 
some  independence  during  his  short  tenure  of  the 
peerage  by  opposing  the  Duke  of  Buckingham.  He 
had,  however,  spent  his  large  revenues  too  lavishly 
and  been  obliged  to  get  a  private  act  of  Parliament  to 
enable  him  to  sell  some  entailed  estates.  His  death, 
20th  June  1628,  was  said  to  have  been  hastened  by 
"excessive  indulgence  in  good  living."  Hobbes 
naturally  does  not  mention  this  in  his  dedication ;  but 
he  suffered  from  the  consequences. 

The  widowed  countess,  left  with  three  children, 
the  eldest  son  eleven  ( years  old,  set  about  regulating 
her  affairs  as  became  her  Scottish  descent.  She  was 
an  intelligent  and  energetic  woman,  admired  in  later 
years  by  Edmund  Waller  and  others,  and  on  friendly 
terms  with  Hobbes.  The  retrenchments,  however, 
which  she  thought  necessary,  involved  his  leaving  his 
old  situation,  and  he  had  to  look  out  for  other  means  of 
support.  He  accepted  the  position  of  travelling  tutor 
to  the  son  of  Sir  Gervase  Clinton,  of  an  old  Notting- 
hamshire family.  A  letter  from  WQ-frton^  to  Sir 
ThjomjLSLffientworth  (4th  April  1628)  mentions  the  lad : 
"Pray  tell  him  (Sir  G.  Clinton)  that  when  he  sent  his 
son  hither  (to  Eton  of  which  Wotton  was  then  provost) 
he  honoured,  and  when  he  took  him  away  he  wounded 
us.  For  in  this  Royal  Seminary  we  are  in  one  thing 
and  only  one  like  the  Jesuits,  that  we  all  joy  when  we 
get  a  spirit  upon  whom  much  may  be  worked."  We 
may  hope,  therefore,  that  Hobbes  had  a  satisfactory 
pupil.  They  were  abroad  for  eighteen  months.  An 


j.]  LIFE  17 

undated  letter  mentions  an  intended  visit  to  Venice, 
probably  prevented  by  war.  Hobbes  was  now  forty,  a 
time  by  which  a  man's  intellect  is  generally  ripe  and 
his  aspirations  tolerably  fixed.  He  had  passed  years 
in  quiet  study,  and  must  have  been  interested  in  the 
political  questions  which  were  becoming  daily  more 
pressing  in  England.  He  must,  one  supposes,  have 
had  comparisons  suggested  to  him  by  the  state  of 
things  in  France,  where  Richelieu  was  building  up  the 
great  state  which  most  nearly  represented  his  own 
ideal  "  Leviathan,"  while  in  the  country  of  Machia- 
velli  he  would  be  led  to  observe  the  famous  con- 
stitution of  Venice,  admired  by  so  many  of  his 
contemporaries  as  the  highest  achievement  of  political 
architecture,  and  would  have  his  own  thoughts  about 
the  great  spiritual  power  which  now  occupied  the  seat 
of  the  Roman  empire.  Hobbes's  method,  however, 
involves  little  appeal  to  observation  of  particular 
events  or  to  his  own  personal  experience,  however 
deeply  they  may  have  impressed  him.  He  tells  us, 
on  the  other  hand,  of  one  discovery  which  was  cer- 
tainly borne  in  upon  him  during  this  journey,  while 
another  may  probably  belong  to  it  or  to  his  next  visit 
to  the  continent.  The  incidents  might  as  well  have 
occurred  at  London  as  in  Paris.  The  first  is  best 
told  by  Aubrey :  "  Being  in  a  gentleman's  library 
Euclid's  Elements  lay  open,  and  'twas  the  47th  EL 
libri  I.  He  read  the  proposition.  '  By  God,'  sayd  he, 
'  this  is  impossible '  '  (he  would  now  and  then  swear  by 
way  of  emphasis,  as  Aubrey  apologetically  notes).  "  So 
he  reads  the  demonstration  of  it  which  referred  him 
back  to  such  a  proposition :  which  proposition  he  read. 
That  referred  him  back  to  another,  which  he  also  read. 


18  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Et  sic  deinceps  that  at  last  lie  was  demonstratively 
convinced  of  that  truth.  This  made  him  in  love  with 
geometry."  The  knowledge,  it  must  be  admitted,  came 
rather  late,  and  the  ignorance  is  not  to  the  credit  of 
his  early  instructors.  As  I  shall  have  to  say,  however, 
the  effect  upon  his  later  speculations  was  of  singular 
importance.  The  second  incident,  whenever  it  hap- 
pened, was  equally  fruitful.  He  was  at  a  gathering  of 
u  learned  men,"  where  something  was  said  about  sen 
sation.  One  of  them  asked,  as  in  contempt,  what  was 
sense  ?  Hobbes  thereupon  wondered  how  it  happened 
that  men  who  took  such  pride  in  the  title  of  "  wise ' 
could  be  ignorant  of  the  nature  of  their  own  senses. 
Thinking  over  the  matter  himself,  he  remarked  that 
if  all  things  were  at  rest  or  all  moved  alike,  there 
could  be  no  difference  of  things  and  consequently  no 
sense.  He  inferred  that  the  cause  of  all  things  must 
be  sought  in  the  difference  of  their  movements.  This 
again  threw  him  back  upon  geometry,  and  led  him  to 
what  he  took  to  be  his  great  discoveries.  Such  is  the 
difference,  is  his  comment,  between  those  who  seek  for 
truth  by  their  own  genius,  and  those  who  seek  it  by 
consulting  authority  or  for  purposes  of  gain.  What- 
ever may  be  thought  of  his  principles,  he  is  certainly 
a  remarkable  instance  of  an  active  mind  set  at  work 
by  remarks  which  others  pass  by  as  common-places.  I 
shall  have  to  speak  hereafter  of  the  essential  part  which 
these  two  doctrines  played  in  his  later  speculation.1 

1  There  are  certain  difficulties  about  the  date  of  the  conver- 
sation "with  learned  men"  :  and  the  discovery  by  Dr.  Tunnies 
of  a  MS.  treatise  in  Hobbes's  hand,  giving  an  early  version  of 
his  doctrine,  rather  complicates  the  question  as  to  the  evolution 
of  his  thought.  I  need  not,  however,  go  into  these  details.  See 
Robertson,  p.  35  n. 


i.]  LIFE  19 

It  is  for  the  present  enough  to  observe  that  we  may 
consider  Hobbes  as  engaged  in  the  elaboration  of  his 
philosophy  from  this  period.  He  had  hitherto,  after 
learning  the  futility  of  the  Oxford  scholasticism,  been  . 
interested  in  literature  and  especially  in  the  historians, 
with  reference,  no  doubt,  to  the  political  questions  of 
the  time.  He  now  took  up  philosophy  again  from  the 
scientific  and  mathematical  side,  and  elaborated  the* 
ambitious  scheme  of  which  I  shall  speak  presently. 
It  implied,  as  we  shall  see,  that  he  cast  aside  authority 
and  considered  himself  to  be  capable  of  founding  a 
new  system  of  thought  by  his  own  unaided  genius. 
For  a  while,  however,  he  had-  employment  which 
must  have  occupied  much  of  his  time.  In  1631  he 
was  invited  to  return  from  Paris  to  superintend  the 
education  of  the  third  Earl  of  Devonshire,  the  son  of 
his  old  patron  or  pupil,  now  about  fourteen  years  of 
age.  He  was  beginning  to  be  absorbed  in  his  new 
studies,  but  accepted  a  task  which  would  still  leave 
him  some  leisure,  and  to  which  he  thought  himself 
bound  by  gratitude  to  the  family.  He  taught  the  boy 
industriously,  seeking  to  imbue  him  "  with  all  such 
opinions  as  should  incline  him  to  be  a  good  Christian, 
a  good  subject,  and  a  good  son."  The  lessons  included 
Latin  composition,  astronomy,  geography,  logic,  and 
law.  An  abstract  of  Aristotle's  Rhetoric,  which  appears  I 
in  his  works,  was  dictated  to  the  pupil  in  Latin.  The 
boy  was  docile  and  intelligent,  and  in  later  years 
revered  and  protected  his  teacher.  The  recall  of 
Hobbes  by  the  countess  shows  that  his  discharge  had 
not  implied  disapproval.  In  later  }Tears  the  son,  upon 
coming  of  age,  was  dissatisfied  with  some  of  his  mother's 
dispositions  of  the  estate.  Hobbes  went  into  the 


20  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

matter  with  the  son  and  helped  to  arrange  terms  of 
agreement.  He  persuaded  the  young  man  to  give  up 
the  intention  of  legal  proceedings,  and  to  remain  in 
his  mother's  house.  In  the  document  which  records 
the  result,  he  notes  that  he  has  not  acted  for  a  reward, 
but  simply  as  discharging  the  duty  of  a  faithful  tutor. 
/To  this  period  belongs  a  correspondence  with  anoiJier 
member  of  the  family,  William  Cavendish,  Earl  and 
afterwards  Duke  of  Newcastle,  son  of  a  third  son 
of  "  Bess  of  Hardwick,"  and  first  cousin  therefore  to 
the  second  Earl  of  Devonshire.  The  duke's  claim  to 
literary  glory  is  founded  upon  his  books  upon  horse- 
manship, though  he  also  wrote  comedies,  and  colla- 
borated with  his  second  wife,  the  famous  and  eccentric 
Margaret,  in  some  of  her  voluminous  plays.  He  was 
a  man  of  considerable  intelligence,  who  is  said  to  have 
been  a  patron  of  Descartes  and  Gassendi,  as  well  as 
of  Hobbes.  Hobbes  writes  to  him  in  January  1633 
about  an  expected  work  from  Galileo,  which  he  has 
endeavoured  to  procure  for  the  earl  in  London. 
Later  correspondence  shows  that  Hobbes  was  employed 
in  elaborating  his  philosophy  and  counting  upon  New- 
castle's sympathy. 

In  1634  Hobbes  started  for  his  third  visit  to  the 
continent,  accompanying  his  pupil  on  the  usual  grand 
tour.  They  were  at  Paris  in  October,  and  afterwards 
visited  Italy,  returning  again  to  Paris.  This  tour 
marks  Hobbes's  first  recognition  by  philosophical  con- 
temporaries. He  was  at  Florence  in  April  1636, 
anxious,  as  he  says  in  a  letter,  to  read  Heylin's  History 
of  the  Sabbath,  and  Seldeu's  Mare  Clamum.  At  this 
time,  too,  he  saw  Galileo,  who  had  lately  made  his 
famous  recantation,  and  was  living  near  Florence  as  a 


i.]  LIFE  21 

prisoner  of  the  Inquisition.  He  was  admitted  to  the 
friendship  of  the  great  man,  whom  he  mentions  in  his 
books  with  profound  respect.  "Not  long  afterwards, 
Galileo  had  another  remarkable  English  visitor,  John  / 
Milton.  What  he  thought  of  them  we  unfortunately' 
do  not  know  ;  but  each  of  them  carried  away  character- 
istic impressions.  During  this  whole  journey  Hobbes's 
mind  was  always  employed  upon  one  topic.  Whether 
he  was  in  a  ship  or  a  carriage  or  on  horseback,  he  was 
meditating  upon  the  nature  of  the  world,  and  working 
out  the  idea  which  had  struck  him  at  that  "  meeting  of 
learned  men."  There  was,  he  held,  but  one  real  thing 
in  the  world,  the  basis  of  all  that  we  falsely  take  to  be 
things,  and  which  are  mere  phantasms  of  the  brain. 
The  one  reality  is  motion,  and  to  study  the  modes  of 
motion  is  therefore  the  necessary  condition  for  all 
successful  researches  in  science.  Full  of  this  thought, 
he  reached  Paris  and  communicated  it  to  a  remarkable 
man  who  approved  and  brought  it  to  the  notice  of 
others. 

Hobbes  was  fortunate  in  his  new  acquaintance. 
Marin  Mersenjie,  a  man  of  his  own  age,  belonged  to  the 
Friars  Minim  of  the  Franciscan  Order,  and  was  living 
in  a  monastery  near  the  Place  Royale.  Before  leaving 
the  college  of  La  Fleche  he  had  known  Descartes,  his 
junior  by  eight  years,  who  had  entered  the  same  college 
and  already  shown  his  precocity.  Some  years  later 
the  acquaintance  was  renewed,  and  Mersenne  encour- 
aged Descartes  to  devote  his  life  to  study.  He  became 
Descartes's  most  trusted  and  ardent  friend,  and  acted 
as  his  "  plenipotentiary  '  when  Descartes  retired  to 
Holland.  He  accepted  his  friend's  doctrines,  defended 
him  against  accusations  of  heterodoxy,  attracted  dis- 


22  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

.  *~ 

ciples,  and  effected  reconciliations  (when  possible)  with 
enemies.  Mersenne  was  himself  on  friendly  terms 
with  thinkers  of  opposite  schools.  He  had  some 
scientific  ability,  and  had  lately  published  a  transla- 
tion of  Galileo's  Mechanics,  which  made  the  author's 
reputation  in  France.  He  appears  to  have  been  a  man 
of  singular  simplicity  and  kindliness  of  nature,  and  his 
cell  in  the  monastery  became  the  place  of  meeting  for 
the  savants  of  Paris,  and  for  distinguished  strangers. 
He  discharged,  as  Baillet  (the  biographer  of  Descartes) 
put  it,  the  same  function  in  the  republic  of  letters  as 
the  heart  discharges  in  the  human  body.  Hobbes  says 
that  his  cell  was  preferable  to  all  the  schools  of  philo- 
sophers. The  star  of  every  art  (he  becomes  quite 
poetical  in  his  enthusiasm)  revolved  round  Mersenne 
as  the  axis  of  its  orbit.  The  little  constellation  of 
shining  lights,  who  in  those  days  were  dispelling  the 
old  darkness  and  revealing  the  foundation  of  modern 
science,  was  widely  scattered,  and  often  its  component 
stars  were  isolated.  They  had,  it  is  true,  the  advan- 
tage of  a  common  language ;  but  there  were  no 
scientific  societies  or  journals,  and  to  facilitate  their 
intercourse,  and  make  each  aware  of  what  was  being 
done  by  others,  was  a  valuable  service  for  which 
Mersenne  was  especially  qualified.  Hobbes  was  wel- 
comed by  him,  and  began,  as  he  puts  it,  "to  be 
numbered  among  the  philosophers."  He  thus  received 
a  kind  of  honorary  diploma  entitling  him  to  speak 
with  authority.  He  was  not  loath  to  accept  the 
position.  That  a  man  who  had  not  seen  Euclid  till  he 
was  forty,  and  had  only  taken  up  philosophy  at  a  later 
period,  should  claim  before  he  was  fifty  to  be  on  terms 
of  equality  with  the  leaders  of  thought  throughout  the 


i.]  LIFE  23 

whole  range  of  human  knowledge  would  now  seem 
preposterous.  But  physical  science  was  still  in  its 
germ,  and  philosophy,  making  a  fresh  start,  was  pro- 
nouncing study  of  the  old  doctrines  to  be  rather  an 
encumbrance  than  an  advantage.  The  field  to  be 
covered  was  so  small  that  Hobbes,  like  Bacon  or 
Descartes,  might  claim  to  survey  the  whole  intellectual 
world  and  lay  down  the  law  upon  things  in  general. 

Henceforth  Hobbes  was  a  man  with  a  mission.  He 
had  still  to  elaborate  the  details  of  his  creed,  but  the 
first  principles  were  already  clear  to  him.  Before 
dealing  with  his  career  as  the  expounder  of  a  philo- 
sophy, I  may  make  one  remark  suggested  by  his 
alliance  with  Mersenne.  Hobbes's  ethical  theories  have 
been  condemned  as  egoistical  and  cynical ;  and  it  might 
be  inferred  that  these  unpleasant  qualities  were  the 
reflection  of  his  personal  character.  Of  the  ethics  I 
shall  speak  hereafter;  but  the  inference  as  to  char- 
acter requires,  to  say  the  least,  very  important 
reservations.  It  would  be  altogether  unjust  to 
down  Hobbes  as  a  man  of  cold  nature.  Whether  he 
was  a  man  to  make  any  romantic  sacrifice  to  friendship^ 
may  indeed  be  doubted.  Retired  philosophers  may 
congratulate  themselves  that  they  are  seldom  exposed 
to  such  trials,  and  in  Hobbes's  life  the  case  did  not 
occur.  But  everything  goes  to  show  that  he  was  a 
man  of  kindly,  if  not  of  ardent  affections.  Few  men 
appear  to  have  won  so  many  friends  or  to  have  retained 
them  so  permanently.  His  long  connection  with  the 
Cavendish  family  proves  the  existence  of  a  mutual 
esteem  creditable  to  both  sides.  His  language  about 
Mersenne  is  as  warm  and  sincere  as  his  language  about 
his  early  friend  the  second  earl.  The  friendship  with 


24  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Mersenne  led  to  an  equally  warm  friendship  with 
Gassendi  and  with  many  distinguished  men.  Hobbes 
got  into  plenty  of  controversies,  and  the  philosopher  was 
assailed  more  bitterly  than  any  thinker  of  his  time.  It 
is  the  more  remarkable  that  no  serious  imputation  is 
made  upon  the  man.  Clarendon,  when  confuting  his 
abominable  doctrines,  declares  that  Hobbes  was  one  of 
his  oldest  friends,  and  emphatically  asserts  the  personal 
esteem  entertained  by  himself  and  others  for  his  antag- 
onist. Hobbes  seems  to  have  been  personally  attractive 
to  everybody  whom  he  met.  He  was  a  pleasant  com- 
panion, and  clearly  had  wit  enough  to  be  acceptable  in 
every  circle.  But  no  spiteful  sayings  are  attributed  to. 
him,  and,  although  he  quarrelled  over  geometry,  he 
excited  no  personal  antipathy.  Certainly  we  cannot 
claim  for  him  the  posthumous  affection  which  is 
bestowed  upon  men  of  the  heroic  type  like  his  con- 
temporary Milton,  or  of  the  saintly  type  like  Arch- 
bishop Leighton.  But  neither  of  those  eminent 
persons  made  any  mark  in  philosophical  speculation. 
We  must  admit  the  excellence  for  its  own  purpose  of 
more  than  one  type.  A  man  who  is  above  all  to  be  a 
cool  reasoner  and  to  shrink  from  no  conclusion  forced 
upon  him  by  his  logic,  is  a  very  valuable  person,  and 
may  be  forgiven  if  his  spiritual  temperature  does  not 
rapidly  rise  to  boiling-point  and  obscure  his  clearness 
of  vision.  Hobbes,  if  one  may  venture  to  say  so,  had 
probably  quite  as  much  benevolence  as  was  good  for  a 
metaphysician. 

Hobbes  returned  to  England  in  1637,  and  began  at 
once  to  compose  his  exposition.  He  was  still  em- 
ployed by  his  pupil,  who  came  of  age  in  1638,  and  in 
1639  he  was  helping  to  arrange  matters  between  the 


i.]  LIFE  25 

young  earl  and  his  mother.  To  this  time  also  must 
be  chiefly  referred  his  intercourse  with  the  remarkable 
group,  affectionately  commemorated  by  Clarendon. 
Its  most  attractive  member  was  LordJFalkjand,  who 
has  won  the  regard  of  posterity  by  the  charm  of  his 
character  rather  than  by  any  special  achievement.  He 
lived  at  Tew,  a  few  miles  from  Oxford,  and,  according 
to  Clarendon's  account,  kept  open  house  for  all  the 
most  distinguished  members  of  the  university.  Among 
the  men  who  could  drop  in  and  make  free  use  of  his 
table  and  library,  were  the  divines,  Sheldon  and 
Morley,  afterwards  bishops,  and  Hammond  and 
ChilliogBtorth,  who  died  before  the  Restoration,  while  i 
occasional  wits  and  poets  came  over  from  London.  I 
Whether  Hobbes  was  ever  of  the  party  does  not 
appear.  Falkland,  however,  according  to  Aubrey,  was 
"his  great  friend  and  admirer";  and  besides  Claren-"' 
don  himself,  one  who  afterwards  gave  substantial 
proof  of  his  regard  was  Sidney  GodQlphin,  a.  pnpt  of 
some  reputation.  If  Hobbes  joined  the  circle,  he 
would  not  find  its  opinions  altogether  congenial. 
There  was  not  much  love  lost  between  him  and  actual 
or  potential  bishops ;  and  Morley,  Sheldon,  and  Ham- 
mond would  be  too  strictly  orthodox  for  his  taste. 
Falkland,  Chillingworth,  and  their  friend,  the  "ever 
memorable''  John  Hales,  represented  a  rationalising 
movement  within  the  church,  and  were  suspected  of 
"  socinianism."  Of  one  of  them,  Hobbes  made  a  char-  *•** 
acteristic  remark  to  Aubrey.  He  commended  Chilling- 
worth  for  a  very  great  wit :  "  But,  my  God, "  said  he 
(swearing  by  way  of  emphasis  again),  "  he  is  like  some 
lusty  fighters  that  will  give  a  damnable  back-blow 
now  and  then  on  their  own  party."  Chill  in  gworth's 


26  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

vigorous  logic  shows  an  intellect  congenial  to  that  of 
Hobbes  himself;  but  Hobbes  would  no  doubt  think 
that  his  rationalism  logically  led  to  opinions  lying 
beyond  the  borders  of  orthodoxy.  In  politics  there ' 
was  a  similar  relation.  Falkland  was  taken  by  Matthew 
Arnold  as  embodying  the  sweet  reasonableness  which 
condemns  extremes  on  all  sides.  We  hear  him  still 
"  ingeminating  peace ';  after  swords  were  drawn  —  a 
most  amiable  but  unfortunately  a  rather  futile  pro- 
ceeding. He  and  Clarendon  were  constitutionalists,*/ 
opposed  equally  to  the  extreme  claims  of  king  and 
parliament,  though  when  it  became  necessary  to  take  a 
side,  they  preferred  the  royalist  cause.  A  character- 
istic passage  in  the  Behemoth  speaks  of  the  bad  advice 
given  by  men  —  Hobbes  declines  to  revive  old  bitter- 
ness by  giving  their  names  —  who  believed  in  "mixed 
monarchy,"  which  in  reality  is  pure  "  anarchy." 

Hobbes  might  be  contrasted  with  Falkland.  Though  / 
Falkland  was  moderate  enough  to  see  faults  on  both 
sides,  he  was  ready  to  fight  and  indeed  to  throw  away 
his  life  for  the  side  which  was  least  to  blame.  Hobbes 
had  no  doubt  upon  political  or  any  other  questions  ;>/ 
but  he  was  quite  clear  that  he  would  fight  for  neither 
side.  Fighting  he  might  fairly  urge  had  never  been 
his  trade,  and  he  was  clearly  too  old  to  take  it  up. 
Meanwhile  political  controversy  was  raging  with  in- 
creasing bitterness,  and  must  have  occupied  the 
thoughts  of  every  one  with  whom  Hobbes  might  con- 
verse. No  doubt  eager  discussions  were  going  on  in 
the  Falkland  circle.  Hobbes  conceived  that  he  had 
something  to  say  of  considerable  importance,  and  pro- 
bably exaggerated  the  attention  which  logic  was  likely 
to  receive  in  the  disturbed  atmosphere. 


i.]  LIFE  27 

The  exaction  of  ship-money  in  1637  had  led  to— 
the  famous  proceedings  against  Hampden,  and  the 
decision  against  him  in  1638.  The  Scots  were  be- 
coming restive  under  the  imposition  of  the  new 
liturgy ;  they  were  swearing  to  the  covenant  in  1638 ; 
and  in  1639  a  Scottish  army  was  successfully  resisting 
the  king,  and  receiving  the  sympathy  of  the  popular 
party  in  England.  Charles  was  forced  to  appeal  to  a 
parliament  in  April  1640,  after  eleven  years,  during 
which  that  troublesome  body  had  been  suspended. 
Men  were  discussing  fundamental  political  principles, 
and  ready  to  settle  them  by  an  appeal  to  the  sword. 
It  was  time,  thought  Hobbes,  to  speak  out.  He  had 
formed  and  begun  to  execute  a  remarkable  plan.  He  / 
intended,  like  a  sound  logician,  to  lay  down  the  firsti 
principles  of  all  scientific  inquiry,  to  apply  them  to 
what  we  should  now  call  psychology,  setting  forth  the 
laws  of  human  nature,  and  finally  to  found  upon  this 
basis  a  science  corresponding  to  modern  sociology.  He 
now  dropped  the  first  part  and  wrote  a  little  treatise  in 
two  sections,  omitting  the  first  principles,  but  giving 
first  a  summary  of  his  psychology,  and  secondly  his 
political  doctrine.  The  treatise  was  circulated  in 
manuscript  and  occasioned  much  talk  of  the  author. 
Had  it  not  been  for  the  dissolution  of  the  Short 
Parliament,  it  would,  as  he  thought,  have  brought  him 
into  danger  of  his  life.  The  Long  Parliament,  how- 
ever, which  met  in  November,  ready  to  fall  upon 
Strafford,  might  find  time  also  to  deal  with  the  author 
of  this  treatise. 

Hobbes,  "  doubting  how  they  would  use  him,  went 
over  into  France  the  first  of  all  that  fled,  and  there 
continued  eleven  years,  to  his  damage  some  thousands 


28  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

of  pounds  deep."  It  does  not  appear  how  lie  arrived 
at  this  estimate.  Few  other  men  would  have  prided 
themselves  on  being  the  first  to  run  away,  and  it 
may  be  doubted  whether  it  proved,  as  he  apparently 
thought,  his  foresight,  or  implied  an  erroneous  appre- 
ciation of  the  danger.  The  treatise  is  undoubtedly  a 
remarkable  book,  and  gives  the  pith  of  his  most/ 
characteristic  teaching.  Still  he  avoids  so  carefully 
any  direct  reference  to  any  passing  event  that  it  \ 
might  have  failed  to  attract  notice.  Hobbes  might  [ 
surely  have  given  credit  to  members  of  parliament  for 
sufficient  stupidity  to  overlook  logical  implications. 
If  indeed  they  thought  him  worth  punishing,  no  weak 
crotchet  about  liberty  of  the  press  would  have  re- 
strained them.  The  House  of  Commons  was  quite 
ready  to  suppress  objectionable  writers.  Hobbes  him- 
self says  he  was  preaching  the  same  doctrine  as^Bishop 
Manwarhig.  Manwaring  had  been  a  victim  of  the 
parliament  of  1628,  for  sermons  attributing  absolute 
authority  to  the  king.  When  the  parliament  was 
dissolved  the  king  had  pardoned  and  preferred  him, 
and  the  Short  Parliament  found  time  to  fall  upon  him 
again  and  send  him  to  the  Tower.  Hobbes's  treatise 
argues  that  the  "sovereignty"  is  one  and  indivisible, 
and  necessarily  carries  with  it  the  right  to  make  peace 
or  war  and  to  levy  taxes.  Sovereignty,  as  he  truly 
says,  was  then  admitted  to  be  in  the  king,  and  it 
follows  that  Charles  could  raise  ship-money  or  what- 
ever taxes  he  pleased.  If  parliament  were  equal  to 
drawing  that  inference,  and  thought  Hobbes's  treatise 
of  sufficient  importance,  they  would  have  little  scruple  / 
about  applying  the  arguments  directed  against  Man- 
waring. 


i.]  LITE  29 

Hobbes's  political  theory  was  fully  formed  before 
the  outbreak  of  the  war.  He  watched  the  events 
with  interest,  but  of  course  knew  beforehand  that 
they  would  only  confirm  his  theory.  That  result  is 
sufficiently  set  forth  in  the  Behemoth  -  -  a  history  of 
the  period,  written  in  1668,  to  explain  the  causes  of, 
the  rebellion.  The  book  has  a  certain  interest  at  this 
point  in  throwing  some  light  upon  Hobbes's  sympa- 
thies when  the  war  was  actually  raging.  Hobbes  was 
not  yet  a  historical  philosopher  to  the  point  of  scien- 
tific impartiality.  He  too  often,  like  many  better 
historians,  finds  it  enough  to  explain  events  by  the 
wickedness  of  the  other  side.  That  agreeable  theory 
is  an  excuse  for  not  attempting  to  discover  the  causes, 
of  discontent ;  a  wicked  man  wants  no  cause.  He 
gives  occasionally  a  quaint  enough  argument.  The 
king's  soldiers  were  as  stout  as  their  enemies,  but 
could  not  fight  so  keenly  "because  their  valour  was 
not  sharpened  so  with  malice."  To  this  he  adds  the 
additional  reason  that  there  were  many  raw  London 
apprentices  in  the  parliamentary  army  "  who  would 
have  been  fearful  enough  of  death  approaching  visibly 
in  glistening  swords ;  but,  for  want  of  judgment, 
scarce  thought  of  such  death  as  comes  invisibly  in  a 
bullet,  and  therefore  were  very  hardly  to  be  driven 
out  of  the  field."  Hobbes  had  clearly  not  been  under 
fire. 

He  had  plenty  to  say  that  is  more  to  the  purpose, 
and  expressed  with  his  usual  terse  and  pointed  style. 
One  line  of  remark  is  characteristic.  A  letter  to  the. 
Earl  of  Devonshire,  in  August  1641,  discusses  a  peti- 
tion against  bishops.  Hobbes  thinks  that  it  proves 
the  existence  of  many  abuses,  and  heartily  approves 


30  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

of  a  proposal  to  give  more  authority  to  the  laity. 
"  Ministers,"  he  thinks,  "  should  minister  rather  than 
govern."  Experience  teaches  that  "the  dispute 
between  the  spiritual  and  the  civil  power  has  of  late, 
more  than  anything  in  the  world,  been  the  cause  of 
civil  wars  in  all  places  of  Christendom."  He  already 
holds  the  view  which  becomes  prominent  in  the 
Behemoth.  He  starts  with  a  long  comparison  of  the 
claims  of  the  Papacy  and  their  evil  results ;  only  at 
the  end  he  remembers  that,  however  many  crimes  the 
popes  may  have  committed,  they  are  scarcely  to  be 
accused  of  having  prompted  the  Puritan  revolt.  The 
Papists,  he  has  to  explain,  would  not  be  sorry  for 
disorders  that  might  possibly  clear  the  way  for  the 
restoring  of  the  pope's  authority.  The  Puritans  are 
most  clearly  responsible.  "  After  the  Bible  was  trans- 
lated in  English,  every  man,  nay  every  boy  and1 
woman,  thought  they  spoke  with  God  Almighty  and 
understood  what  He  said,  when  by  a  certain  number 
of  chapters  a  day  they  had  read  the  Scriptures  once  or 
twice  over."  They  lost  their  reverence  for  the  bishops, 
and  were  supported  by  the  gentry,  who  desired  popular 
government  in  civil  matters  as  non-conformists  did 
in  ecclesiastical.  Thus  supported,  the  presbyterian 
preachers  went  on  to  declaim  against  tyranny.  They 
played  the  part  of  "  right  godly  men  as  skilfully  as 
any  tragedian  in  the  world."  They  took  care  indeed 
not  to  inveigh  against  the  lucrative  vices,  such  as 
lying,  cozening,  and  hypocrisy,  "which  was  a  great 
ease  to  the  generality  of  citizens  and  the  inhabitants 
of  market  towns,  and  no  little  profit  to  themselves." 
"  The  inhabitants  of  market  towns '  were  already 
fertile  in  the  Stigginses  of  the  period.  Hobbes  detests 


i.]  LIFE  31 

the  Presbyterians  more  than  the  Independents ;  for 
the  Presbyterian  claimed  a  spiritual  authority  over  the 
State  for  his  own  church;  still  his  preaching  led  to 
the  multiplication  of  sects.  "  There  was  no  so 
dangerous  an  enemy  to  the  Presbyterians  as  this 
brood  of  their  own  hatching."  The  Rump,  he  observes, 
voted  liberty  of  conscience  to  the  sectaries  and  so 
"  plucked  out  the  sting  of  presbytery,"  a  feat  which 
was  personally  useful  to  Hobbes  himself.  Meanwhile 
the  established  church  had  its  faults.  The  clergy  in 
general  thought  that  the  pulling  down  of  the  pope 
was  the  setting  up  "  of  them  in  his  place."  Their 
doctrine  of  apostolical  succession  implied  that  their 
"spiritual  power  did  depend  not  upon  the  authority 
of  the  king  but  of  Christ  himself."  He  admits  that 
Laud  was  a  "  very  honest  man,"  but  intimates  that  he 
was  a  very  poor  statesman  for  mixing  state  affairs 
with  his  "  squabblings  in  the  university  about  free 
will,  and  his  standing  upon  punctilios  concerning  the 
service  book  and  its  rubrics." 

Though  an  absolutist  in  politics,  Hobbes  can  cor- 
dially denounce  persecution.     "A  state  can  constrain 
obedience  but  convince  no  error,  nor  alter  the  mind  of 
them  that  think  they  have  the  better  reason.     Sup- 
pression of  doctrines  does  but  unite  and  exasperate  : 
that  is,  increase  both  the  malice  and  the  power  of  them 
that  have  already  believed  them."     Persecution  results 
from  the  desire  of  the  spiritual  power  to  enforce  the— 
dogmatic  systems  learnt  in  the  schools.      "Religion 
has   been   generally  taken   for   the  same   thing  withV 
divinity  (that  is,  with  metaphysical  theology),  to  the 
great  advantage  of  the  clergy."     Though  the  translan 
tion  of  the  Bible  did  mischief,  he  approves  of  it  on  the  ' 


32  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

• 

whole.  The  Bible  teaches  good  morality  in  the  easiest 
words.  The  mischief  resulted  from  the  use  of  the, 
Scriptures  in  controversies  over  mysteries.  It  is  only 
when  the  State  is  subordinate  to  the  Church  that 
abstract  dogmas  will  be  enforced  by  law,  and  it  is  only 
in  Christian  countries  that  there  have  been  wars  of 
religion,  because  there  men  have  been  encouraged  to 
wrangle  and  harangue  upon  such  points.  The  intro- 
duction of  this  scholastic  dogmatism  is  a  main  count 
in  his  indictment  against  the  universities.  "  The 
universities  have  been  to  this  nation  as  the  wooden 
horse  was  to  the  Trojans."  They  are  the  "core  of 
rebellion."  It  might  have  been  said  that  the  revival 
of  classical  literature  was  a  point  in  their  favour.  But 
that  only  suggests  another  charge.  They  taught  men 
to  argue  "for  liberty  out  of  the  works  of  Aristotle, 
Plato,  Cicero,  and  Seneca,  and  out  of  the  histories  of 
Koine  and  Greece  "  — not,  it  would  seem,  paying  proper 
attention  to  Thucydides.  Things  will  never  be  well 
till  they  are  reformed  and  made  to  teach  absolute 
obedience  to  the  laws  of  the  king  "  and  his  public 
edicts  under  the  great  seal  of  England " :  that  is,  as 
one  of  his  opponents  sneered,  till  the  Leviathan  has 
become  the  accepted  text-book. 

Hobbes  on  reaching  Paris  had  renewed  his  old  rela- 
tions Avith  Mersenne,  and  his  first  bit  of  work  was  a 
return  to  purely  philosophical  activity.     Descartes  had 
published  his  famous  treatise  on  Method  in  1637,  andl 
was   now  about   to  follow  it  up   by  the  Meditations.\ 
Mersenne  had  submitted  the  book  before  publication 
to  various  learned  men  who  were  to  offer  criticisms 
which,  with  Descartes's  replies,  might  be  expected  to 
throw  light  upon  any  obscurities  in  the  new  system' 


i.]  LIFE  33 

Hobbes  came  just  iu  time  to  join  in  this  operation. 
He  put  certain  objections  briefly  and  bluntly,  and 
they  are  of  much  interest  as  illustrating  his  own  rela- 
tion to  Descartes.  But  they  did  not  answer  the 
intended  purpose.  Descartes  had  expected,  and  he 
more  or  less  received  from  others,  the  rare  and  useful 
kind  of  criticism  which  comes  from  thinkers  who  are 
sufficiently  in  sympathy  with  their  author  to  draw 
from  him  additional  explanations  of  his  thought  and 
help  him  to  round  off  and  perfect  his  exposition.  But 
Hobbes  differed  radically.  The  controversy  very 
rapidly  reached  the  point  at  which  flat  contradiction 
takes  the  place  of  friendly  argument,  and  Descartes 
did  not  like  contradiction  for  its  own  sake  any  more 
than  any  other  philosopher.  Instead  of  a  partial  ally 
he  found  a  dogged  opponent,  and  one  who  thought 
himself  entitled  to  speak  with  fully  equal  authority. 
Descartes  naturally  became  convinced  that  Hobbes 
was  a  very  poor  philosopher.  There  was  not,  he  said, 
a  single  sound  conclusion  in  the  objections.  Matters 
did  not  improve  when  Mersenne  forwarded  to  Des- 
cartes certain  objections  to  his  Dioptrique.  In  order  to 
secure  a  fair  hearing,  Mersenne  concealed  the  fact  that 
these  objections  also  were  made  by  Hobbes.  Descartes 
did  not  suspect  the  little  artifice,  but  did  not  like  the 
new  objections  any  better.  He  would,  he  said,  have 
nothing  more  to  do  with  the  Englishman.  At  a  later 
period  Descartes  admitted  that  Hobbes  was  a  more 
competent  writer  upon  political  problems  than  upon 
metaphysical  and  mathematical  questions,  although 
his  political  principles  were  morally  objectionable. 
He  held  that  all  men  were  wicked  and  gave  them 
ground  for  wickedness.  Hobbes  on  his  side,  according 

D 


34  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

to  Aubrey,  had  a  "  high  respect "  for  Descartes,  but  / 
thought  that  "  his  head  did  not  lie  for  philosophy  "  : 
he  ought  to  have  confined  himself  to  geometry.  He 
could  not  pardon  him  for  writing  against  his  con- 
science in  defence  of  "  transubstantiation  in  order  to 
please  the  Jesuits."  This  unsatisfactory  encounter  did 
not  long  detain  Hobbes.  His  interest  in  the  political 
issues  of  the  civil  war  continued,  and  his  thoughts 
were  for  ten  years  "much  or  almost  altogether 
unhinged  from  the  mathematics."  The  first  result  of 
his  meditations  was  the  De_  Give,  (1642)  t  which  is  sub- 
stantially a  remodelling  of  the  political  part  of  the 
"little  treatise."  It  was  written  in  Latin,  by  way 
apparently  of  implying  that  it  was  intended  for  the 
philosophical  world  of  Europe,  and  only  a  small 
number  of  copies  was  printed. 

Hobbes  then  began  the  composition  of  his  most 
famous  work,  the  Leviathan.  This  time  he  used  hisy 
native  language,  and  meant,  it  is  to  be  presumed, 
to  catch  the  attention  of  the  politicians  who  were 
remoulding  the  constitution  of  his  own  country.  The 
Leviathan,  like  the  early  treatise,  covers  the  second 
and  third  parts  of  his  general  plan,  the  first  principles 
being  again  postponed.  It  is  always  easy  to  supply 
first  principles  when  you  have  settled  your  conclusions. 
One  characteristic  may  be  noted.  In  the  first  treatise^ 
he  had  asserted  his  principle  of  the  subordination  of 
the  Church  to  the  State.  This  argument,  however, 
was  greatly  expanded  in  the  De  Cive,  and  now  in 
the  Leviathan  fills  a  still  larger  space.  For  whatever 
reason,  Hobbes's  antipathy  to  the  claims  of  the  spiritual 
powers,  whether  Catholic  or  Presbyterian,  had  been 
growing  in  intensity.  The  Leviathan,  which  Hobbes 


i.]  LIFE  35 

hoped,  and  not  without  reason,  would  make  an  epoch 
in  political  speculation,  was  carefully  and  slowly 
written.  Aubrey  describes  his  method.  "  He  walked 
much  and  contemplated ;  and  he  had  in  the  head  of 
his  staff  a  pen  and  ink  horn ;  carried  always  a  note- 
book in  his  pocket,  and  as  soon  as  a  thought  darted, 
he  presently  entered  it  into  his  book,  or  otherwise  he 
might  perhaps  have  lost  it.  He  had  drawn  the  design 
of  the  book  into  chapters,  etc.,  so  that  he  knew 
whereabouts  it  would  come  in."  The  composition  took 
some  years,  during  which,  one  would  suppose,  Hobbes 
must  have  been  often  in  financial  straits.  Mersenne's 
failure  to  bring  him  into  friendly  relations  with 
Descartes  did  not  prevent  the  continuance  of  his 
own  friendship.  Another  conspicuous  member  of  the 
Mersenne  circle,  held  to  be  only  second  to  Descartes, 
was  Gassendi.  He  settled  in  Paris  as  professor  of 
mathematics  in  1645,  and  became  a  warm  friend. 
Hobbes  called  Gassendi  the  "  sweetest-natured  man  in 
the  world,"  and  Gassendi  expressed  the  highest  ad- 
miration for  Hobbes's  writings.  A  less  distinguished 
acquaintance,  Sorbisre,  was  rather  a  hanger-on  than  a 
member  of  the  circle.  He  wrote  books  upon  medical 
topics,  and  vainly  tried  to  get  patronage  from  the 
pope  for  his  conversion  from  protestant  error,  but 
neither  the  pope  nor  other  observers  seem  to  have 
considered  him  as  particularly  edifying.  Meanwhile 
he  boasted  of  his  friendship  for  Gassendi,  whose  life 
he  wrote.  He  also  professed  admiration  for  Hobbes, 
who  allowed  him  to  publish  a  definitive  edition  of  the 
De  Give  at  Amsterdam.  It  was  delayed  until  1647, 
when  it  came  out  accompanied  by  two  most  enthusi- 
astic letters  of  commendation  from  his  friends  Mer- 


36  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

senne  and  G-assendi.     Of  one  other  friend  and  warm 
admirer  we  know  little.    This  was  Pu  Yerdus,  a  noble 
of  Languedoc.      They  had  become  so  intimate  that 
Hobbes  was  about  to  give  up  all  hopes  of  returning 
to  England,  and   to   settle  with  Du  Verdus  in  the  i 
country,  when  a  new  career  seemed  to  open  for  him  J 
on  the  arrival  of  the  Prince  of  Wales  in  Paris. 

English  refugees  had  been  following  the  first  fugi- 
tive. The  Cavendish  family  had  taken  the  royalist 
side.  Hobbes's  pupil,  the  third  earl,  had  been  im- 
peached in  1642,  and  escaped  to  the  continent.  He 
returned  to  England  in  1645,  submitted  to  the  parlia- 
ment, and  lived  in  retirement  at  Latimers  in  Bucking- 
hamshire till  the  Restoration.  His  younger  brother, 
Charles,  had  distinguished  himself  on  the  king's  side 
at  Edgehill,  but  was  killed  in  an  encounter  with 
Cromwell  in  1643.  Their  mother,  Christiana,  remained 
in  England,  and  her  house  was  a  meeting-place  of 
the  royalist  party,  by  whom  she  was  fully  trusted. 
Their  cousin,  the  Earl  of  Newcastle,  commanded  the 
king's  forces  in  the  north,  and  when  his  army,  then 
led  by  Prince  Rupert,  was  crushed  at  Marston  Moor, 
he  left  England  and  reached  Paris  in  the  spring  of 
1645.  He  stayed  there  three  years,  and  his  presence 
was,  no  doubt,  important  to  Hobbes.  His  wife  repeats 
a  conversation  between  them,  at  which  Newcastle 
spoke  sceptically  of  witchcraft,  and  according  to 
her,  suggested  a  passage  to  the  same  effect  in  the 
Leviathan.  Possibly  the  lady  was  claiming  a  little  too 
much  for  her  husband.  Bramhall,  Bishop  of  Derry, 
had  escaped  with  Newcastle,  and  had  a  discussion  with  \ 
Hobbes  about  free  will  at  the  house  of  the  marquis  / 
(as  he  had  now  become).  Each  of  the  disputants 


i.]  LIFE  37 

afterwards  put  his  arguments  in  writing ;  but  Hobbes 
desired  that  his  paper  should  be  kept  private.  He 
had  allowed  a  copy  to  be  taken  for  a  friend,  which 
was  afterwards  published  without  his  consent,  with 
results  to  be  presently  noticed.  IJldnmnd  Waller  told 
Aubrey  that  he  had  met  Plobbes,  Gassendi,  and 
Descartes  dining  together  at  the  marquis's  table  in 
Paris.  With  the  marquis  at  this  time  was  his 
brother.  Sir  Charles  Cavendish,  who  had  been  pre- 
vented by  deformity  from  bearing  arms,  and  had 
taken  to  mathematics.  He  collected,  says  Aubrey,  as 
many  mathematical  MSS.  as  filled  a  hogshead,  intending 
to  publish  them.  But  he  died  "  of  the  scurvy  con- 
tracted by  hard  study,"  and  his  papers,  falling  into 
ignorant  hands,  were  sold  by  weight  to  the  paste- 
board makers.  Petty  mentions  Hobbes's  kindness  in 
introducing  him  to  the  two  brothers.  Petty,  most 
versatile  and  ingenious  of  men,  was  thirty-five  years 
younger  than  Hobbes.  He  was  precocious  from 
childhood,  and  at  this  juncture  was  in  Paris  with 
an  introduction  to  Hobbes  from  the  English  mathe- 
matician Pell.  Petty  helped  Hobbes  by  drawing 
figures  for  his  optical  propositions ;  and  the  two 
joined  in  reading  Vesalius's  anatomy.  Petty  was  soon 
afterwards  lecturing  on  anatomy  at  Oxford.  The 
economic  writings  by  which  he  is  remembered,  show 
marked  traces  of  Hobbes's  political  influence.  About 
this  time,  1646,  Clarendon,  writing  at  Jersey  on  his 
way  to  Holland,  sent  a  message  to  Hobbes  asking  for 
the  De  Cive,  and  told  him  that  their  common  friend, 
Sidney  Godolphin,  slain  at  Chagford  in  the  beginning 
of  1645,  had  left  him  a  bequest  of  £200.  Hobbes 
received  £100,  with  a  promise  of  the  rest  from 


38  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Godolphin's  brother,  to  whom,  though  personally 
unknown,  he  dedicated  the  Leviathan  in  gratitude. 
At  the  end  of  the  book  he  makes  a  striking  reference 
to  his  friend.  "  I  have  known  clearness  of  judgment 
and  largeness  of  fancy,  strength  of  reason  and  grace- 
ful elocution,  a  courage  for  the  war  and  a  fear  for  the 
laws  and  all  eminently  in  one  man ;  and  that  was  my 
most  noble  and  honoured  friend,  Mr.  Sidney  Godol- 
phin,  who,  hating  no  man,  nor  hated  of  any,  was 
unfortunately  slain  in  the  beginning  of  the  late  civil 
war,  in  the  pubjic  quarrel,  by  an  undiscerned  and 
undiscerning  hand."  The  bequest  must  have  been 
welcome.  It  was  not  so  easy  to  make  communications 
or  send  remittances,  and  Hobbes  only  heard  of  his 
legacy  by  the  accident  of  Clarendon's  letter,  some 
little  time  after  Godolphin's  death.  The  Cavendishes 
had  plenty  of  calls  upon  their  money,  and  had  other 
things  to  think  of  than  Hobbes's  fortunes. 

The  gathering  of  the  exiles  at  Paris  naturally  led 
to  Hobbes's  appointment  to  be  mathematical  tutor  to 
the  Prince  of  Wales.  It  was,  we  may  suppose,  not  a 
very  splendid  post  if  regarded  from  a  pecuniary  point 
of  view.  Newcastle  had  been  for  a  time  the  prince's 
"  governor,"  and  had  drawn  up  a  paper  of  instructions, 
superfluously  advising  that  the  boy  should  not  be  too 
devout,  "  and  should  be  very  civil  to  women."  He 
might  now  naturally  recommend  his  friend  Hobbes, 
whose  qualifications  were  indeed  ample.  Mersenne 
had  published  some  of  his  scientific  speculations. 
Pell  had  at  this  time  confuted  one  Longomontanus, 
who  claimed  to  have  squared  the  circle ;  and  Hobbes 
was  invited  along  with  Descartes  and  other  leading 
mathematicians,  including  Sir  Charles  Cavendish,  to 


i.]  LIFE  39 

pronounce  an  opinion  upon  the  controversy.  How 
far  he  succeeded  in  impressing  the  prince  with  his 
reverence  for  Euclid  does  not  appear.  At  a  later 
time  the  conjunction  was  regarded  as  fraught  with 
disastrous  consequences.  Burnet  scented  a  diabolical 
plot.  The  Duke  of  Buckingham,  such  was  the  sug- 
gestion, desired  to  corrupt  Charles's  morals  and 
principles.  Buckingham  would  be  in  no  need  of  help 
in  the  moral  department,  but  he  introduced  Hobbes 
to  inculcate  "  political  and  religious  schemes,"  which 
made  a  deep  impression  upon  the  pupil,  "  so  that  the 
main  blame  of  the  King's  ill  principles  and  bad  morals, 
was  owing  to  the  Duke  of  Buckingham."  As  a  matter 
of  fact,  Hobbes  states  in  a  letter  to  Sorbiere  that  he 
was  confined  to  mathematical  teaching,  the  prince 
being  too  young  for  philosophy.  It  would  be  more 
plausible  to  attribute  to  his  influence  Charles's  most 
creditable  peculiarity  —  a  certain  interest  in  science. 
Ill  principles  were  abundant  enough  in  the  atmo- 
sphere of  the  court.  The  connection  lasted  at  most 
for  two  years,  as  Charles  came  to  Paris  in  1646,  and 
left  it  for  Holland  in  the  spring  of  1648.  He  retained, 
however,  a  friendly  feeling  for  his  tutor.  The  new 
edition  of  the  De  Give  was  now  on  the  point  of  publi- 
cation, and  Sorbiere,  in  1647,  proposed  to  describe 
Hobbes  on  the  title-page  as  tutor  to  the  Prince  of 
Wales.  Hobbes  objected  in  a  remarkable  letter.  The 
connection  of  the  writer  may  do  harm  to  the  prince, 
as  suggesting  that  he  approves  Hobbes's  principles. 
Courtiers  may  accuse  him  of  vanity.  Finally  he  may 
think  of  returning  to  England  if  peace  is  established 
in  any  way.  He  did  not,  he  said,  belong  to  the  house- 
hold, and  apparently  found  it  already  uncongenial. 


40  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Hobbes's  teachersliip  was  interrupted,  if  not  ter- 
minated, by  a  severe  illness  which  brought  him  to  the 
point  of  death  in  1647.  He  gives  a  characteristic 
anecdote  in  regard  to  it.  Mersenne  was  called  in  by 
a  common  friend,  who  feared  that  Hobbes  would  die 
outside  of  the  Roman  communion.  Mersenne  accord- 
ingly came  and  began  a  discourse  upon  the  power  of 
his  church  to  remit  sins.  "Father,"  said  Hobbes,  "I 
have  long  gone  over  that  question  in  my  own  mind. 
You  have  something  pleasanter  to  say.  When  did 
you  see  Gassendi  ? '  Mersenne  dropped  the  subject. 
Soon  afterwards  Co  sin,  afterwards  Bishop  of  Durham, 
offered  his  services,  and  Hobbes  received  the  sacrament 
from,  him  according  to  the  Anglican  rite :  a  great 
proof,  he  observes,  of  his  reverence  for  the  episcopal 
discipline.  Aubrey  gives  a  very  different  version  of 
the  story.  When  divines  came  to  him  in  this  illness, 
he  said,  "  Let  me  alone,  or  else  I  will  detect  all  your 
cheats  from  Aaron  to  yourselves."  But  Hobbes's  own 
account  must  be  preferred.  Mersenne  died  in  Sep- 
tember 1648,  after  great  suffering  under  the  hands  of 
blundering  surgeons.  Hobbes  continued  to  work  at 
his  political  writings.  In  1650  he  published  or 
allowed  the  publication  of  the  little  treatise  which  had 
remained  for  ten  years  in  manuscript,  and  in  1651  he 
published  an  English  translation  of  the  De  Cive.  The 
poet  WaJIej?  had  offered  to  translate  it  before,  but 
having  asked  Hobbes  to  translate  part  by  way  of 
model,  declined  to  undertake  a  task  which,  as  he 
sensibly  judged,  could  be  executed  by  no  one  so  well 
as  the  author  himself.  These  two  books  were  fore- 
runners of  the  Leviathan,  which  was  printed  in  London, 
and  appeared  in  the  middle  of  1651.  In  August 


i.]  LIFE  41 

Hobbes  had  another  illness,  of  which  the  shrewd  and 
learned  physician,  Gui  Patin,  gives  a  lively  account. 
He  was  called  in  to  see  Hobbes,  whom  he  describes  as 
stoical,  melancholy,  and  outre  cela  Anglais.  Naturally, 
therefore,  he  had  been  thinking  of  suicide ;  Englishmen 
have  a  turn  that  way.  He  refused  to  be  bled :  the 
remedy  for  almost  all  diseases  according  to  Patin. 
Next  day,  however,  he  gave  in,  to  his  great  benefit. 
They  at  once  became  camarades  et  grands  amis  ;  and 
Patin  allowed  him  to  drink  as  much  small  beer  as  he 
liked.  Hobbes  was  in  the  habit  of  saying  that  he 
would  prefer  an  old  woman  who  had  been  at  many  bed- 
sides to  the  "  learnedst  young  unpractised  physitian." 
The  fate  of  his  friend  Mersenne  ma}T  have  weakened 
his  faith  in  the  faculty.  Two  months  after  his  re- 
covery Charles  reached  Paris  after  his  final  defeat  at 
Worcester,  and  Hobbes  speedily  presented  him  with  a 
manuscript  copy  of  the  Leviathan,  "  engrossed  in  vellum 
in  a  marvellous  fair  hand."  It  is  now  to  be  seen  in 
the  British  Museum. 

The  immediate  consequence  was  that  Hobbes  had 
to  retreat  to  England,  and  became  the  object  of 
accusations  which  require  notice,  not  because  they 
are  plausible  but  because  they  illustrate  his  position 
at  the  time.  Wallis,  in  a  controversy  with  Hobbes 
after  the  Restoration,  declared  that  the  Leviathan 
was  "writ  in  defence  of  Oliver's  title."  Claren- 
don reports  that  he  talked  with  Hobbes  shortly 
before  the  book  was  published.  Hobbes  showed  him 
some  sheets  and  spoke  of  his  opinions.  Clarendon 
asked  how  he  could  publish  such  doctrine  ?  After  a 
"  discourse  between  jest  and  earnest,"  Hobbes  replied : 
"The  truth  is  I  have  a  mind  to  go  home."  Conver- 


HOBBES  [CHAP. 

sations  between  jest  and  earnest  reported  twenty 
years  later  are  unsatisfactory  evidence,  and  it  is  more 
likely  that  the  grave  Clarendon  failed  to  see  a  joke 
than  that  Hobbes  meant  to  make  such  a  confession. 
To  Wallis  he  made  a  sufficient  answer.  Cromwell 
did  not  become  protector  till  1653,  and  it  could 
not  be  known  in  1650  that  he  was  the  right  person 
to  flatter.  But  besides  this  the  argument  of  the 
Leviathan  was  certainly  not  modified  in  order  to 
please  either  Cromwell  or  the  Rump,  to  which  for 
the  present  he  was  subordinate.  The  principles  are 
identical  with  those  of  the  early  treatise  and  the 
De  Give  written  long  before;  and  since  they  were 
L<not  modified  at  all,  they  were  not  modified  in  order 
to  curry  favour  with  anybody.  Things,  it  is  true, 
had  changed,  and  it  might  be  suggested  that  the 
defence  of  the  absolute  power  of  the  sovereign  was 
applicable  to  parliament,  when  it  became  sovereign, 
as  it  had  once  been  applicable  to  the  king.  But 
parliament  would  certainly  not  admit  that  only  by 
success  were  its  claims  justified,  or  approve  of  a 
doctrine  which  condemned  the  whole  rebellion.  In 
any  case  it  is  scarcely  fair  to  blame  Hobbes,  who 
laid  down  a  perfectly  consistent  doctrine  from  first  to 
last,  if  a  change  of  circumstances  made  the  doctrine 
agreeable  to  a  new  order.  The  truth  is,  I  take  it, 
that  his  view  was  one  which  could  not  be  openly 
avowed  even  by  Cromwellians  or  by  royalists.  The 
more  they  might  act  in  accordance  with  it,  the  more 
anxious  they  would  be  to  disavow  it. 

There   was,   however,    one   part   of    the   Leviathan 

I  which    might   be   a   stumbling-block.       In   a   Review 
and    Conclusion   he   briefly   considered   the   question, 


i.]  LIFE  43 

at  what  time  does  a  subject  become  obliged  to  a 
conqueror  ?  He  answers  that  "  it  is  when  the  means 
of  his  life  are  within  the  guards  and  garrisons  of 
the  enemy."  Submission,  therefore,  to  a  de  facto 
government  is  right ;  and  Hobbes  adds  that  such 
submission  is  not  even  an  assistance  to  the  new 
power,  which  would  otherwise  confiscate  an  oppo- 
nent's whole  property  instead  of  taking  a  part.  This 
was  a  convenient  argument.  In  1656  Hobbes  could 
take  credit  for  the  influence  of  the  Leviathan  in 
framing  "the  minds  of  a  thousand  gentlemen  to  a 
conscientious  obedience  to  the  present  government 
(Cromwell's),  which  otherwise  would  have  wavered 
in  that  point."  In  1662  he  looks  at  the  question 
from  the  other  point  of  view,  and  remembers  that 
by  "compounding'3  they  diminished  the  plunder  of 
the  usurper,  and  in  due  time  would  be  better  able 
to  serve  the  king.  That  was  the  case  of  many 
honourable  persons,  including,  it  may  be  observed, 
Hobbes's  own  patron  the  Earl  of  Devonshire.  No 
moralist,  I  suppose,  would  deny  that  such  submission 
becomes  right  in  time.  Nobody  could  blame  an 
elderly  scholar,  who  had  no  position  under  the 
exiled  king,  for  settling  down  quietly  in  his  native 
country  and  justifying  the  same  action  in  his  friend's 
case.  No  doubt,  however,  the  doctrine  gave  offence 
to  those  who  held  out.  "Mr.  Hobbes,"  writes  Sir 
Edward  Nicholas  in  February  1652,  "is  at  London 
much  caressed  as  one  that  hath  by  his  writings 
justified  the  reasonableness  and  righteousness  of  their 
arms  and  actions."  Hobbes  had  certainly  not  done 
that ;  but  the  royalist  might  be  scandalised  when  an 
eminent  writer,  who  had  previously  been  the  king's 


44  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

tutor,  defended  submission  to  the  powers  in  existence, 
and  so  far  admitted  the  cause  to  be  hopeless.  How 
far  he  was  "  caressed  "  does  not  appear.  He  certainly 
got  nothing  from  the  government,  and  he  had  very 
sufficient  reasons  for  leaving  France. 

Nicholas  was  then  in  Holland  and  previous  notes 
of  his  are  significant.  "All  honest  men  here/7  he 
says  in  January,  "are  very  glad  that  the  K.  hath 
at  length  banished  from  his  court  that  father  of 
atheists,  Mr.  Hobbes,  who,  it  is  said,  hath  rendered 
all  the  queen's  court,  and  very  many  of  the  D.  of 
York's  family  atheists,  and  if  he  had  been  suffered, 
would  have  done  his  best  to  have  likewise  poisoned 
the  king's  court."  A  very  few  days  later  he  regrets 
that  Papists  "  (to  the  shame  of  the  true  Protestants) 
were  the  chief  cause  that  that  grand  atheist  was 
v/sent  away."  He  mentions,  but  declines  to  believe, 
a  report  that  the  Marquis  of  Ormonde  was  very 
slow  in  signifying  the  king's  command  to  Hobbes 
to  forbear  coming  to  court.  Clarendon,  who  seems 
to  have  had  some  part  in  the  expulsion,  had  now 
read  the  printed  book  and  told  Hobbes  that  "  such  a 
book  would  be  punished  in  any  country  in  Europe." 
He  says  that  Hobbes  had  to  "fly  secretly,  the  justices 
having  endeavoured  to  apprehend  him."  Hobbes  him- 
self says  that  the  Anglican  prelates  had  found  fault 
with  the  theology  of  his  book,  and  that  he  was  in 
fear  of  the  Catholic  clergy,  whose  church  he  had 
certainly  attacked.  Whether  Hobbes  could  rightly 
called  an  atheist  is  a  question  to  be  noticed  here- 
after. His  friend  Mersenne  had  declared  some  years 
before  that  there  were  some  50,000  atheists  in  Paris 
alone,  and  that  twelve  might  be  often  found  in  one 


i.]  LIFE  45 

house.  As  there  was  no  religious  census  at  the  time 
the  numbers  must  be  considered  as  distinctly  con- 
jectural. "  Atheism,"  however,  is  a  word  which  could 
be  and  was  used  simply  as  a  missile  to  be  hurled 
at  anybody  morally  or  philosophically  objectionable. 
Both  Hobbes's  friends,  Gassendi  and  Mersenne,  were 
Catholic  ecclesiastics  who  discharged  their  functions 
regularly,  and  Gassendi  maintained  that  his  admira- 
tion for  Epicurus  was  consistent  with  thorough 
orthodoxy.  Hobbes  can  hardly  have  talked  atheism 
to  them,  and  the  anecdote  about  Mersenne  and  Bishop 
Cosin,  to  which  he  refers  so  complacently,  seems  to 
imply  that  he  was  as  reticent  as  might  be  expected 
from  his  timidity.  Perhaps  he  had  been  more  out- 
spoken among  the  courtiers,  and,  at  any  rate,  the 
attacks  upon  the  spiritual  power  in  his  two  last 
books  meant  an  attitude  towards  the  Church  which 
might  well  suggest  "atheism,"  as  Mersenne  under- 
stood the  word,  even  to  candid  critics.  Certainly 
he  had  said  enough  to  shock  the  Catholic  authori- 
ties, and  his  fear  of  their  action  was  natural.  Besides 
this,  he  tells  us  that  he  was  frightened  by  the  murder 
of  the  two  English  envoys  in  Holland  and  Spain, 
Dorislaus  and  Ascham.  He  was  in  an  awkward 
position.  Charles,  he  admits,  was  set  against  him. 
The  young  king  "trusted  in  those  in  whom  his 
father  had  trusted,"  says  Hobbes.  Hobbes  was 
hardly  called  upon  to  stay  in  a  place  where  his 
countrymen  and  the  native  authorities  agreed  in 
considering  him  to  be  an  atheist,  and  held  atheism 
to  be  not  only  damnable  but  criminal. 

He  was  glad   to   escape   to   England   in   a   severe 
winter,   and   suffering   from    his   infirmities,   and   to 


46  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

settle  among  old  friends  in  a  land  where  he  was  at 
least  permitted  to  publish  his  writings.  Three  months 
later  (as  he  declared)  he  went  more  than  a  mile  to 
take  the  sacrament  according  to  the  Anglican  rite. 
He  made  his  submission  to  the  Council  of  State  and 
remained  for  the  rest  of  his  life  in  England.  In  1653 
he  again  became  a  member  of  the  Earl  of  Devonshire's 
family.  The  earl,  though  living  in  retirement  at 
Latimers  in  Buckinghamshire,  also  occupied  "Little 
Salisbury  House ';  in  London.  Hobbes  complained 
that,  although  the  earl  had  a  good  library  and  pro- 
vided his  old  tutor  with  all  the  books  he  wanted,  a 
country  life  gave  small  opportunities  for  "learned 
conversation."  One's  understanding,  Aubrey  said,  as 
Johnson  might  have  said,  "  grows  mouldy."  He 
appears  to  have  spent  most  of  his  time  in  London, 
and,  as  at  all  periods  of  his  life,  cultivated  the 
friendship  of  the  most  distinguished  contemporaries. 
He  was  on  intimate  terms  with  the  best  known  poets, 

Davenant.      IVIilton  would  not 

be  a  congenial  friend.  TnTiis  last  year  at  Paris  he 
had  been  very  intimate  with  Davenant,  who  was  then 
writing  the  first  cantos  of  his  ponderous  epic  Gondibert. 
He  submitted  it  as  it  was  written  to  Hobbes,  and 
addressed  a  very  long  preface  to  his  friendly  critic. 
Hobbes  replied  in  a  letter  which  was  printed  as  an 
appendix  to  the  preface.  It  is  superfluous  to  say  that 
each  expresses  a  very  high  opinion  of  the  other's 
merits.  I  need  not  dwell  upon  Hobbes's  aesthetic 
doctrine.  "  A  poet,"  he  says,  "  ought  to  know  well, 
and  to  know  much " :  a  sign  of  the  first  is  "  perspi- 
cuity, propriety,  and  decency  " ;  a  sign  of  the  second 
is  "  novelty  of  expression,  which  pleaseth  by  excitation 


i.]  LITE  47 

of  the  mind,  for  novelty  causeth  admiration  and 
admiration  curiosity,  which  is  a  delightful  appetite 
of  knowledge."  He  ends  by  a  spirited  protest  against 
Davenant's  depreciation  of  old  age  as  second  child- 
hood. ".That  saying,  meant  only  of  the  weakness 
of  the  body,  was  wrested  to  the  weakness  of  mind  by 
fro  ward  children,  weary  of  the  controlment  of  their 
parents,  masters,  and  other  admonitors."  The  dotage 
of  age  is  "  never  the  effect  of  time  but  sometimes  of 
the  excesses  of  youth."  "  Those  who  pass  their  youth 
in  making  provision  only  for  their  ease  and  sensual 
delight  are  children  still  at  what  years  soever :  as 
they  that  coining  into  a  populous  city,  never  going 
out  of  their  inn,  are  strangers  still,  how  long  soever 
they  have  been  there."  There  is,  moreover,  "no 
reason  for  any  man  to  think  himself  wiser  to-day  than 
yesterday,  which  does  not  equally  convince  he  shall 
be  wiser  to-morrow  than  to-day."  Davenant  will  love 
to  change  his  opinion  when  he  becomes  old,  and 
"  meanwhile  you  discredit  all  I  have  said  before  in 
your  commendation  because  I  am  old  already." 
Hobbes  was  not  quite  sixty-two  when  he  wrote  this 
and  was  to  live  nearly  thirty  years  longer.  He  did 
his  best  to  act  up  to  his  encouraging  but  rather 
questionable  doctrine,  and  took  the  approach  of  old 
age  with  all  possible  gallantry.  Old  age  was  then 
considered  to  begin  at  a  comparatively  early  period, 
and  Hobbes,  in  spite  of  the  antagonism  which  he 
excited,  enjoyed  some  of  its  privileges.  Cowley's 
ode  to  him.  written  some  years  later  touches  the 
point : 

"Nor  can  the  snow  which  now  cold  age  does  shed, 
Upon  thy  reverend  head 


48  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Quench  or  allay  the  noble  fires  within, 

But  all  which  thou  hast  been 

And  all  that  youth  can  be  thou' rt  yet, 

So  fully  still  dost  thou 

Enjoy  the  manhood  and  the  bloom  of  wit 

And  all  the  natural  heat  but  not  the  fever  too." 

A  phenomenon  which  is  accounted  for  in  the  familiar 
lines : 

"  To  things  immortal  time  can  do  no  wrong, 
And  that  which  never  is  to  die  for  ever  must  be  young." 

Cowley  says  that  the  scholastic  philosophy,  of  which, 
as  his  poems  show  he  had  made  some  study,  was  now 
dead,  and  that  Hobbes  is  the  great  "  Columbus  of 
the  golden  land  of  new  philosophies."  Hobbes' s  three 
poetical  friends  had  probably  all  known  him  in  France. 
Waller  had  an  unfortunate  facility  for  turning  his  coat, 
and  came  back  about  the  same  time  as  Hobbes  ;  he 
was  pardoned  and  then  patronised  by  Cromwell,  and 
afterwards  reconciled  himself  to  Charles  II.  Davenant 
finished  his  Gondibert  in  the  Tower,  but  was  after- 
wards allowed  to  revive  theatrical  performances  before 
the  Restoration.  Cowley,  who  had  been  trusted  in 
confidential  employment  by  Henrietta  Maria,  was 
suspected,  like  Hobbes,  of  a  disposition  to  reconcile 
himself  to  the  actual  authorities,  but  seems  to  have 
been  a  consistent  royalist. 

Hobbes  had  two  other  remarkable  friends.  One  was 
Harvey  (1578-1657),  whose  great  discovery  of  the 
circulation  of  the  blood  had  been  first  published  in 
1616,  and  of  whom  Hobbes  always  speaks  with  pro- 
found admiration.  Harvey  is  said  to  have  left  him 
£10  in  his  will.1  The  other  was  John  Selden  (1584- 

1  Aubrey  reports  that  Selden,  like  Harvey,  left  £10  to  his 
friend,  but  this  seems  to  be  au  error. 


i.]  LIFE  49 

1654).  Their  acquaintance  began  by  Hobbes  sending 
him  a  copy  of  the  Leviathan,  after  which,  says  Aubrey, 
there  was  a  strict  friendship  between  them.  The  con- 
versations between  the  authors  of  the  Leviathan  and 
the  Table  Talk  would  no  doubt  be  worth  hearing,  and 

<~ *  / 

Selden's  Erastian  views  would  be  thoroughly  acceptable 
to  Hobbes.  Baxter,  however,  reports,  on  the  authority 
of  Sir  Matthew  Hale,  that  Selden  attacked  Hobbes's 
sceptical  opinions  so  forcibly  as  to  drive  him  out  of  the 
room.  Another  of  Aubrey's  stories  is  that  Hobbes 
dissuaded  Selden  from  sending  for  a  clergyman  when 
he  was  dying.  "  What,"  he  is  supposed  to  have  said, 
"  will  you  that  have  wrote  like  a  man  now  die  like  a 
woman  ? '  As  a  contradictory  account  is  given  of 
Selden's  death,  and  as  Hobbes  certainly  acted  on  the 
opposite  principle  when  he  was  himself  in  danger,  we 
may  probably  assume  that  the  anecdote  represents  not 
what  actually  happened,  but  what  somebody  thought 
would  naturally  be  done  by  an  "atheist." 

Meanwhile  Hobbes  was,  as  he  says,  in  a  country 
where  every  one  might  write  what  he  pleased.  Free 
from  fear  of  priests  and  with  some  gratitude  to 
sectaries,  he  could  sit  down  to  finish  his  philosophy. 
He  had  sufficiently  expounded  his  political  theories, 
and  they  were  provoking  some  controversy.  Filmerj 
(best  known  from  Locke's  attack  upon  his  posthumous 
book,  the  Patriarcha)  criticised  Hobbes  in  1652,  along 
with  Grotius  and  Milton.  Alexander  Ross,  whose 
memory  is  preserved  only  by  a  rhyme  in  Hudibras  as 
to  the  "philosopher  who  had  read  Alexander  Ross 
over,"  animadverted  on  the  Leviathan  next  year.  But 
they  were  opponents  who  might  be  neglected  by  a 
writer  who  had  now  achieved  so  high  a  position. 

£ 


50  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Hobbes  sat  down  to  finish  his  work  by  completing 
the  exposition  of  first  principles,  from  which  he  had 
been  distracted  by  his  interest  in  the  parliamentary 
struggle. 

He  was  presently  interrupted.  The  anonymous 
person  to  whom  he  had  entrusted  a  copy  of  his  dis- 
cussion with  Bramhall  was  now  induced  to  publish 
the  piece  in  which,  as  he  said  in  a  preface,  the  author 
of  the  Leviathan  had  solved  a  question  over  which 
divines  had  wrangled  so  long  and  so  fruitlessly. 
Bramhall  naturally  supposed  that  Hobbes,  who  had 
stipulated  at  the  time  for  privacy,  was  responsible  for 
the  publication.  He  therefore  published  all  that  had 
passed,  with  his  rejoinder  to  Hobbes.  Hobbes  replied 
in  1658,  and  Bramhall  two  years  afterward  came  out  with 
Castigation  of  Mr.  Hobbes's  Animadversions,  together 
with  an  appendix  called  The  Catching  of  Leviathan  the 
Great  Whale.  This  was  meant  to  expose  the  atheistical' 
doctrine  embodied  in  Hobbes's  chief  work.  Bramhall 
died  in  1663,  and  Hobbes,  who  declares  that  he  had  not 
heard  of  the  attack  for  ten  years,  now  made  a  reply 
which  did  not  appear  till  after  his  own  death.  The 
controversy  brought  out  some  of  Hobbes's  most  vigorous 
writing,  and  gives  an  important  part  of  his  philosophy, 
of  which  I  shall  have  to  speak  hereafter.  Hobbes 
meanwhile  had  finished  the  book  which  was  to  give  the 
foundations  of  his  system.  It  was  published  in  Latin 
as  De  Corpore  in  1655.  An  English  translation  (only 
superintended  by  himself)  appeared  in  1656. 

This  book  contains  a  very  important  exposition  of 
Hobbes's  general  principles.  It  also  includes  certain 
very  unfortunate  speculations  which  led  to  one  of  the 
most  singular  tangles  of  controversy  in  which  a  philo- 


i.]  LIFE  51 

sopher  ever  wasted  his  energies.  I  have  already  noted 
Hobbes's  condemnation  of  the  universities,  which  hadx 
found  sufficient  expression  in  the  Leviathan.  Accord- 
ing to  him,  they  still  taught  nothing  but  the  old 
scholasticism,  corrupted  youth  by  classical  republi- 
canism, and  were  ignorant  of  modern  science.  He  was 
not  aware,  it  seems,  of  the  remarkable  change  which 
had  come  over  his  own  university.  In  1619  Sir 
Henry  Savile  had  founded  professorships  of  geometry 
and  astronomy.  Until  that  time,  according  to  Hobbes, 
many  people  regarded  geometry  as  "art  diabolical," 
and  its  professors,  as  Wood  says,  were  taken  to  be 
"  limbs  of  the  devil."  Mathematical  studies  were  now 
gaining  respect,  and  by  the  time  of  Hobbes's  return  to 
England,  Oxford  had  become  the  meeting-place  of  a 
remarkable  number  of  eminent  and  energetic  teachers. 
Never  before  —  perhaps  one  might  add,  not  often  after- 
wards—  was  the  university  so  important  a  focus  of 
scientific  illumination.  Oxford  (alternately  with  Lon- 
don) was  the  headquarters  of  the  remarkable  group  of 
men  who  founded  the  Royal  Society  after  the  Restora- 
tion. Young  men  destined  to  become  famous,  Robert 
Boyle  and  Christopher  Wren  and  Hobbes's  friend, 
Petty,  and  others  less  generally  known,  were  of  the 
number.  Boyle,  the  eldest  of  the  three,  was  thirty-nine 
years  and  Wren  forty -four  years  younger  than  Hobbes. 
They  represented  the  new  generation,  eager  to  enter 
into  that  promised  land  of  science  of  which  Bacon  had 
caught  "  a  Pisgah  sight."  The  two  Savilian  professors, 
both  some  years  older,  were  men  of  mark.  Seth  Ward 
(1617-1689)  had  been  appointed  professor  of  astro- 
nomy in  1649,  though  previously  ejected  from  Cam- 
bridge for  refusing  the  covenant.  He  was  already 


52  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

known  as  an  able  mathematician  though  after  the 
Restoration  he  left  science  to  rise  in  the  Church  and 
become  ultimately  Bishop  of  Salisbury.  John  Wallis 
(1618-1703),  the  professor  of  geometry  from  1649, 
was  a  man  of  singular  acuteness,  and  one  of  the  first 
mathematicians  of  his  day.  His  Arithmetica  Infinitorum, 
published  in  1655,  was  the  greatest  step  towards  the 
development  of  the  differential  calculus,  elaborated  by 
Newton  and  Leibnitz  in  the  next  generation.  Oxford 
while  represented  by  such  men  could  certainly  not  be 
condemned  as  behind  the  time  in  science.  Hobbes, 
who  specially  claimed  to  represent  the  scientific  move- 
ment, should  have  recognised  the  men  who  were  its 
most  efficient  organs.  Unluckily  for  him  things  fell 
out  very  differently.  Ward  replied  to  Hobbes  in  an 
appendix  to  a  book  mainly  directed  against  another 
assailant  of  the  universities.1  In  an  earlier  essay  he 
had  professed  a  high  opinion  of  that  "  worthy  gentle- 
man," Hobbes ;  but  he  now  felt  bound  to  expose  the 
worthy  gentleman's  arrogance  and  ignorance.  Backed 
by  a  letter  from  the  famous  John  Wilkins.  at  this  time 
warden  of  Wadham,  and  afterwards  the  first  secretary 
of  the  Royal  Society,  he  accused  Hobbes  of  plagiarism, 
and  taunted  him  in  advance.  Whenever  Hobbes  pub- 
lished his  geometrical  discoveries  (of  which  he  had 
apparently  been  boasting)  he  would  find  that  they 
were  only  too  well  understood  at  Oxford. 

These  discoveries  saw  the  light  in  the  De  Corpore. 
Hobbes  had  squared  the  circle :  and  though  the  sub- 

1  John  Webster,  known  also  from  his  Displayinc)  of  Supposed 
Witchcraft  (1677),  directed  against  Henry  More  and  other 
credulous  persons  :  and  not  the  famous  dramatist,  as  others 
have  had  to  prove. 


i.]  LIFE  53 

ject  was  strictly  irrelevant,  he  could  not  refrain  from 
introducing  a  chapter  into  his  book  by  way  of  showing 
his  capacity.  He  had  solved  the  problem  which  had 
baffled  all  previous  geometers  from  Archimedes  down- 
ward. No  man  ever  made  a  more  unlucky  boast. 
Ward  and  Wallis  agreed  to  make  an  example  of  the 
rash  intruder  who  had  given  himself  into  their  hands. 
Ward  wrote  against  the  general  philosophy ;  in  that 
department  nothing  could  be  done  beyond  repeating 
familiar  arguments.  Wallis,  who  undertook  the 
mathematics,  had  a  more  satisfactory  task.  Mathe- 
matical controversies  have  the  peculiarity  that  they 
lead  to  definite  issues,  in  which  one  side  must  be 
entirely  in  the  right,  and  the  other  entirely  in  the 
wrong.  Hobbes  had  or  had  not  squared  the  circle,  and 
his  success  or  failure  could  be  clearly  demonstrated  to 
all  competent  people.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  of  course,  he 
had  failed  egregiously.  Not  only  so,  but  he  had  made 
successive  attempts ;  falling  out  of  one  blunder  into 
another,  he  had  left  traces  of  the  process  by  cancelling 
sheets,  and  he  had  shown  a  strange  incapacity  for  even 
appreciating  the  conditions  of  strict  mathematical 
proof.  All  this  Wallis  explained  in  an  Elenchus 
Geometries.  Hobbiance,  adding  reproof  and  ridicule  to 
poison  the  wound  to  his  victim's  vanity.  Hobbes  was 
too  incompetent  even  to  know  that  he  had  been  refuted. 
With  a  courage  worthy  of  a  better  cause  he  defended 
his  own  errors,  and  gave  fresh  proofs  of  incapacity  by 
attacking  Wallis's  real  discoveries  in  Six  Lessons  for  the] 
Oxford  professors.  Wallis  in  return  gave  Due  Correc-l 
tionfor  Mr.  Hobbes  in  School  Discipline  for  not  saying  his 
Lessons  right.  The  language  became  worse,  and  diverged 
into  irrelevant  topics.  Wallis  charged  Hobbes  with 


54  HOBBES  [CHAP. 


confusing     the    Greek    words     ^ny^y    and 
Hobbes's   next  book  was  therefore   headed   " 

Ayeco/zerptas,      'Aypoi/a'a,?,      'Ai/TivroAiTeias,      *A/xa$e«xs     OT 

Marks  of  the  absurd  Geometry,  Rural  Language,  Scottish 
Church  Politics,  and  Barbarisms  of  John  Wallis" 

"When  the  Royal  Society  was  founded,  1662,  Hobbes 
was  naturally  not  invited  to  join  a  body  of  which  his 
antagonists  were  leading  members.  He  showed  his 
anger  by  attacking  Boyle's  account  of  his  experiment 
with  the  air-pump.  He  often  said  that  if  people  who 
tried  such  a  farrago  of  experiments  were  to  be  called 
philosophers,  the  title  might  be  bestowed  upon  apothe- 
caries and  gardeners  and  the  like.  Besides  stating  that 
the  Society  was  on  the  wrong  tack  and  would  learn 
nothing  till  they  adopted  his  principles,  he  indulged 
in  a  personal  fling  at  Wallis.  Wallis  replied  in  the\ 
Hobbius  Heauton  Timoroumenos,  which  seems  to  have 
been  the  most  complete  exposure  of  Hobbes's  manifold 
blunders.  It  gave  Hobbes,  however,  his  one  telling 
retort.  Wallis  made  the  accusation  of  disloyalty  already  - 
noticed.  Hobbes  defended  himself,  and  pointed  out 
that  Wallis  had  deciphered  the  king's  despatches  taken! 
after  Naseby,  and  had  boasted  of  the  fact.  If  Wallis 
now  said  (as  he  seems  to  have  done)  that  he  did  it  to 
the  king's  advantage,  that  would  only  show  that  he 
cheated  his  employer,  excused  treason  with  treachery, 
and  was  a  double  spy.  To  this  awkward  thrust  Wallis 
did  not  reply.  But  it  did  not  prove  that  Hobbes  had 
squared  the  circle. 

The  battle  was  not  yet  ended.  Four  years  later 
(1666)  Hobbes  came  out  with  a  new  treatise,  in  which 
he  admitted  that  all  geometers  were  against  him; 
either  he  alone  must  be  mad  or  he  alone  not  madj 


i.]  LIFE  55 

unless  indeed  they  were  all  mad  together.  He  was  now 
seventy-eight,  but  still  wrote  treatises  to  which  Wallis 
punctually  replied  until  1672,  when  Hobbes  was 
eighty-four.  Wallis  then  dropped  off,  but  Hobbes 
published  yet  another  treatise  in  1674,  and  fired  a 
final  shot  called  the  Decameron  Pliysiologicum  in  1678, 
at  the  ripe  age  of  ninety.1 

There  is  something  pathetic  as  well  as  comical  in 
this  singular  history.  Hobbes  told  Sorbiere  in  1656 
that  he  attacked  the  professors  mainly  because  they 
represented  the  clergy  and  universities.  That  was  a 
very  bad  reason  for  assaulting  his  opponent's  strongest 
side.  The  old  gentleman  certainly  wasted  a  great 
deal  of  time  and  temper,  and  showed  an  amazing 
degree  of  self-confidence.  Still  he  was  near  seventy 
when  the  fight  began,  and  to  a  man  of  that  age  some- 
thing should  be  forgiven  for  intellectual  energy,  even 
in  a  mistaken  cause.  One  remark  may,  I  suppose,  be 
made.  A  man  who  attempted  circle-squaring  at  a 
later  period  proved  himself  to  be  hopelessly  at  sea. 
Many  such  adventurers  are  described  in  de  Morgan's 
very  amusing  Budget  of  Paradoxes.  But  in  Hobbes's 
day  the  enterprise  was  not  so  clearly  perceived  to 
be  hopeless.  He  was  called  in,  as  we  have  seen,  to 


*A  full  account  of  this  controversy  is  given  in  Groom 
Robertson's  IL>bbcs,  pp.  167-185.  I  have  been  content  to 
follow  him,  and  have  not  even  seen  Wallis's  pamphlets,  which 
have  become  rare,  as  he  declined  to  print  them  in  his  works 
after  Hobbes's  death.  Robertson  was  far  more  competent  than 
I  could  be  to  give  an  opinion  upon  the  merits  of  a  controversy, 
which  in  any  case  would  not  deserve  any  lengthy  discussion  in 
the  present  book.  Dr.  Tunnies  thinks  Robertson  rather  hard 
upon  Hobbes,  and  unjust  to  the  historical  significance  of  this 
controversy. 


56  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

arbitrate  in  one  case  of  circle-squaring,  and  his  friend 
Mersenne  had  a  controversy  about  the  same  time  with 
the  Jesuit,  St.  Vincent,  "  the  best  of  circle-squarers." 
To  square  the  circle,  or  in  other  words  to  find  the 
ratio  of  the  radius  to  the  circumference,  was  of  course 
a  rational  problem,  though,  I  suppose,  that  the  proper 
treatment  could  not  be  applied  till  the  development  of 
the  methods  adopted  by  Wallis,  and  so  unfortunately 
misunderstood  by  Hobbes.  He  persistently  protested 
against  the  application  of  algebra  to  geometry :  that 
is  against  the  most  essential  step  in  advance  that  was 
being  made  in  his  day.  He  consequently  made  an 
attempt  in  which  failure  was  inevitable.  De  Morgan, 
however,  seems  to  feel  a  certain  compunction  in 
classing  him  with  the  circle-squarers,  and  says,  that 
in  spite  of  his  blunders  he  shows  great  ability  in  his 
remarks  upon  the  general  theory  of  mathematical 


reasoning. 


The  moral  is,  I  suppose,  that  a  man  ought  to  read 
Euclid  before  he  is  forty.  He  will  assimilate  the 
principles  better,  and  he  will  also  be  made  aware  of 
the  danger  of  mistaking  blunders  for  original  dis- 
coveries. That  is  an  error  of  which  he  will  be  cured 
by  examiners.  Anyhow,  besides  wasting  his  energy, 
Hobbes  had  put  himself  in  a  curiously  uncomfortable 
position  by  the  time  of  the  Restoration.  Intellectual 
audacity  combines  awkwardly  with  personal  timidity. 
The  poor  old  gentleman,  aged  seventy-two,  whose 
great  aim  was  to  keep  out  of  harm's  way,  had  stirred 
up  an  amazing  mass  of  antipathies.  His  political — 
absolutism  was  hateful  to  constitutionalists  like 
Clarendon  as  well  as  to  the  more  popular  politicians  :-s. 
to  the  two  parties,  that  is,  which  were  about  to  become 


i.l  LIFE  57/ 

v — S 

tories  and  whigs.  Anglican  bishops  and  non-con- 
formist divines  agreed  that  he  was  an  atheist,  and  ^ 
what  was  to  some  almost  as  bad,  a  hater  of  all  ecclesi- 
astical authority.  His  political  views  might  suit  the 
courtiers,  but  no  one  could  be  more  hostile  to  their 
leanings  to  Borne.  Political  absolutism  and  religious 
scepticism  made  a  creed  which  could  not  be  openly 
avowed,  though  it  might  and  did  excite  some  tacit 
sympathy.  He  had,  however,  spoken  with  a  certain 
authority  as  a  representative  of  science.  Now  the 
scientific  and  philosophical  world  had  ostracised  him. 
They  had  pronounced  him  to  be  a  charlatan.  A  man 
who  could  make  such  a  mess  of  squaring  the  circle  was 
presumably  a  paradox-monger  in  philosophy.  His 
opponents  would  taunt  him  with  a  failure  admitted  by 
every  one  but  himself.  It  is  true  that  popular  opinion 
looks  upon  philosophers  with  a  dash  of  amused  con- 
tempt. Like  Shakespeare's  fools  they  are  allowed  a 
certain  license.  Their  queer  opinions,  even  if  atro- 
cious, are  so  far  removed  from  practical  business  as  to 
be  harmless  and  rather  amusing  playthings.  Person- 
ally Hobbes  was  generally  agreeable  ;  and  so  venerable 
in  appearance  that  one  would  prefer  to  leave  him  in 
quiet.  He  had  some  anxious  moments,  but  on  the 
whole  was  tolerated. 

Hobbes  had  spent  the  winter  of  1659  in  Derby- 
shire, when  Aubrey  wrote  to  beg  him  to  be  present 
at  the  king's  arrival  in  London.  Hobbes  was 
standing  at  the  gates  of  Little  Salisbury  House 
as  his  majesty's  coach  drove  through  the  Strand. 
Charles  recognised  his  old  tutor,  took  off  his 
hat  and  greeted  him  kindly.  A  week  afterwards 
Hobbes  attended  when  Charles  was  sitting  for  his 


58  HOBBES  [CHAP 

portrait  to  the  famous  miniature  painter,  Samuel 
Cooper,  and  diverted  the  sitter  by  his  "pleasant  dis- 
course.'7 Charles  gave  orders  that  he  should  always 
have  access  to  the  court  —  the  royal  taste  was  good  in 
the  matter  of  "  wit  and  sharp  repartees."  When 
Hobbes  appeared,  the  king  would  say :  "  Here  comes 
the  bear  to  be  baited ; ':  and  the  courtiers  did  their 
best.  Hobbes  feared  none  of  them,  being  "  marvellous 
happy  and  ready  in  his  replies."  He  took  care,  how- 
ever, to  avoid  serious  topics.  During  the  following 
period,  Hobbes  spent  most  of  his  time  in  London. 
Our  next  glimpse  of  him  is  given  by  the  French 
ambassador,  the  Comte  de  Corainges.  Louis  XIV.  had  " 
at  this  time  resolved  to  become  the  patron  of  learned 
men  throughout  Europe.  Cominges  was  directed  to 
inquire  what  men  worthy  of  this  exalted  patronage 
were  to  be  found  in  England.  He  made  the  dis- 
couraging reply  that  arts  and  sciences  had  chosen 
France  as  their  sole  abode.  In  England  men  still 
remembered  Bacon,  Sir  Thomas  More,  and  Buchanan, 
but  the  only  living  author  of  reputation  was  "un 
nomme  Miltonius"  :  an  infamous  person  whose  writings 
would  not  be  to  the  taste  of  the  great  king.  Shortly 
afterwards  he  discovered  Hobbes,  and  invited  him  to 
dinner  along  with  the  famous  mathematician,  Christian 
Huygens,  and  Hobbes's  old  friend  Sorbiere.  The 
"bonhomme"  Hobbes  speaks  enthusiastically  of  Louis, 
and  he  might  truly  be  called  "  assertor  regum  "  (a  title 
which  "  Miltonius r>  clearly  did  not  deserve)  and 
Cominges  would  be  very  glad  to  be  the  means  of 
obtaining  a  pension  for  him.  Never,  he  says,  "  will 
any  favour  have  been  better  placed."  The  application 
was  favourably  received  at  first,  but  nothing  seems  to 


I.]  LIFE  59 

have  come  of  it.  Perhaps  on  inquiry  somebody 
remembered  that  Hobbes  had  left  France  in  bad  odour 
with  the  priests,  to  say  the  least ;  or  Huj^gens,  upon 
whom  a  pension  was  bestowed,  may  have  given  a 
confidential  opinion  about  the  squaring  of  the  circle. 
Hobbes's  friends  anyhow  denied  at  his  death  some 
report  of  a  designed  or  actual  pension.  Charles,  how- 
ever, had  given  him  a  pension  of  £100  a  year.  An 
undated  petition  shows  that  it  had  been  stopped  for 
some  time  along  with  others  ;  but  Hobbes  says  he 
had  enjoyed  it  to  his  great  comfort  for  many  years. 
He  mentions  arrears  in  his  will  (1677).  Sorbiere  next 
year  wrote  an  account  of  his  travels  with  due  compli- 
ment to  Hobbes.  The  third  earl,  he  says,  "  loves  and 
reveres "  his  old  tutor.  He  applies  Charles's  saying 
about  baiting  the  bear  to  the  clergy ;  and  adds :  "  I 
know  not  how  it  comes  to  pass,  the  clergy  are  afraid 
of  him." 

Hobbes  was  certainly  afraid  of  the  clergy.      The 
years  1665  and  1666  were  marked  by  the  plague  and 
the  fire  of  London,  which  naturally  startled  contempo- 
raries.   The  fire  of  London  might  perhaps  be  set  down 
to  the  Papists,  as  was  recorded  on  the  monument,  but 
they  could  hardly  have  been  responsible  for  the  plague. 
That  was  doubtless  a  manifestation  of  Divine  wrath ; 
and   to   the    question,   what    had    provoked   it?    the 
obvious  answer  was,  Hobbes.     A  bill  was  brought  into 
parliament   for  the  suppression  of  atheism  and  pro- 
faneness,  and  a  committee  was  instructed  to  receive 
information  about  " Mr.  Hobbes's  Leviathan"     With  I 
him  was  joined  an  eccentric  Catholic  priest,  Thomas/ 
White  (or  Albius),  known   at  the  time   as  a  contro-f 
versialist.     White  was  suspected  of  heresy.     He  had,' 


60  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

it  seems,  denied  the  "  natural J:  immortality  of  the 
soul.  Hobbes  and  White  were  doubtless  not  the  only 
offenders.  The  court  was  not  perfectly  pure.  The 
bill  passed  the  House  of  Commons  but  was  ultimately 
dropped.  Hobbes  was  frightened,  and  not  without 
reason.  Aubrey  mentions  a  report  (probably  referring 
to  this  time)  that  some  of  the  bishops  made  a  motion 
"  to  have  the  good  old  gentleman  burnt  for  a  heretic." 
Hereupon,  he  says,  Hobbes  put  some  of  his  papers  in 
the  fire.  Hobbes  wrote  an  essay  concerning  heresy  to 
prove  that  he  could  not  be  legally  burnt,  and  protested 
in  an  appendix  to  a  Latin  translation  of  the  Leviathan. 
The  essay  was  not  published,  and  Hobbes  probably 
depended  for  safety  less  upon  his  logic  than  upon 
the  favour  of  Charles  and  of  Arlington.  Arlington, 
the  secretary  of  state,  was  a  concealed  Catholic. 
There  were  plenty  of  "  Hobbists  "  at  the  court  at  this 
time,  as  Clarendon  and  Burnet  sorrowfully  confess. 
Arlington  possibly  preferred  them  to  the  Anglican 
bishops  who  were  more  dangerous  enemies  of  his 
church.  Hobbes,  at  any  rate,  addresses  Arlington  as 
the  special  protector  of  his  old  age.  The  first  result 
was  that  Hobbes  was  not  attacked  but  forbidden  to 
give  further  utterance  to  his  views.  Charles  forbade 
the  publication  of  the  Behemoth,  written  in  1668;  and- 
Pepys  wishing  to  buy  the  Leviathan,  "  which  is  now 
mightily  called  for"  (3rd  September,  1668),  found  that 
he  had  to  pay  twenty-four  shillings  for  a  second-hand 
copy;  whereas  it  had  theretofore  been  sold  for  eight 
shillings.  It  is  now,  he  adds,  sold  for  thirty  shillings. 
The  bishops  would  not  allow  it  to  be  reprinted. 

A   year   latter,    one    Scargill,    a   fellow    of   Corpus 
College,  Cambridge,  having  maintained  some  theses  in 


I.]  LIFE  61 

which  phrases  from  the  Leviathan  were  twisted  to  an 
offensive  meaning,  was  expelled  from  the  university, 
and  induced  to  make  a  public  recantation.  He  had 
gloried  in  being  a  Hobbist  and  atheist,  and  attributed 
his  moral  ruin  to  Hobbes's  principles.  After  this 
alarm,  says  Kennett,  Hobbes  went  more  regularly  to 
the  earl's  chapel,  though  he  would  not  go  to  the 
parish  church.  He  did  not  care  for  sermons.  They 
could  teach  him  nothing  but  what  he  knew.  His  fame 
meanwhile  was  spreading  abroad.  In  1669  he  was 
visited  several  times  by  the  Grand  Duke  of  Tuscany, 
who  took  away  a  portrait  and  works  of  the  philoso- 
pher, to  be  preserved  among  the  most  precious  jewels 
of  the  Medicean  library. 

In  1668  Hobbes  reached  his  eightieth  year,  and 
might  have  had  other  motives  for  silence  than  pro- 
hibitions by  authority.  He  preserved  his  intellectual 
activity,  however,  almost  to  the  last.  Besides  the 
books  mentioned,  he  had,  about  1659,  according  to 
Aubrey,  and  about  his  eightieth  year  according  to  his 
own  account,  written  a  Latin  poem  of  more  than  two 
thousand  elegiacs,  versifying  the  Historia  Universalis 
of  Cluverius,  and  describing  once  more  the  usurpations 
of  the  spiritual  power.  In  1664  Aubrey  begged  him  to 
write  about  law,  when  he  answered  that  he  could  not 
count  upon  life  enough.  Few  men  could  become  law 
students  at  seventy-six.  Aubrey,  however,  sent  him 
Bacon's  Elements  of  the  Common  Laics;  whereupon  he 
set  to  work,  and  produced  a  Dialogue  between  a  Philo- 
sopher and  a  Student  of  the  Common  Laics  of  England. 
His  especial  aim  was  to  confute  Coke,  as  the  wor- 
shipper of  precedent.  The  dialogue  was  not  finished ; 
but  it  is  noticed  by  Maine  as  showing  that  Hobbes 


62  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

had  anticipated  many  of  the  legal  reforms  afterwards 
advocated  by  Bentham.  A  few  years  later  he  retired 
from  controversy  —  not  to  silence,  but  to  a  new  literary 
employment.  In  1673  he  published  the  Voyage  of 
Ulysses :  a  translation  into  English  quatrains  of  Books 
IX.-XII.  of  the  Odyssey.  This,  it  seems,  was  by  way  of 
experiment ;  and  a  year  later  he  produced  a  complete 
translation  both  of  the  Iliad  and  the  Odyssey.  Nobody 
has  yet,  I  believe,  discovered  that  the  work  is  a  worthy 
rival  of  Chapman  or  Pope :  a  task  which  might  per- 
haps have  charms  for  some  literary  revivalists.  The 
severest  critic  might  be  touched  to  silence  at  any  rate 
by  Hobbes's  own  apology  :  "  Why  did  I  write  it  ?  Be- 
cause I  had  nothing  else  to  do.  Why  publish  it  ? 
Because  I  thought  it  might  take  off  my  adversaries 
from  showing  their  folly  upon  my  more  serious  writ- 
ings, and  set  them  upon  my  verses  to  show  their 
wisdom.  But  why  without  annotation  ?  Because  I 
had  no  hope  to  do  it  better  than  it  is  already  done 
by  Mr.  Ogilby."  It  was  at  least  a  creditable  occupa- 
tion for  a  man  of  eighty-six.  I  will  content  myself 
with  quoting  the  passage  which  has  often  been  quoted 
to  prove  that  Hobbes  could  deviate  into  a  really 
poetical  phrase.  It  is  from  the  famous  meeting  of 
Hector  and  Andromache: 

"  Now  Hector  met  her  with  their  little  boy 
That  in  the  nurse's  arms  was  carried, 
And  like  a  star  upon  her  bosom  lay 
His  beautiful  and  shining  golden  head." 

In  1675  Hobbes  left  London  finally,  to  pass  the  last 
four  years  of  his  life  at  Chatsworth  and  Hardwick. 
He  was  still  at  work ;  his  last  scientific  paper  appeared 


i.]  LIFE  63 

when  he  was  ninety,  and  on  the  18th  of  August  1679 
he  tells  his  publisher  that  he  is  writing  somewhat  to 
print  in  English.  In  October  he  was  attacked  by  a 
complaint  incurable  at  his  age.  "  I  shall  be  glad,"  he 
said  upon  learning  it,  "  to  find  a  hole  to  creep  out  of 
the  world  at."  At  the  end  of  November  the  family 
moved  from  Chatsworth  to  Hardwick,  and  Hobbes 
declining  to  be  left  behind,  was  put  upon  a  feather-bed 
in  the  coach.  The  journey  was  too  much  for  his 
strength ;  an  attack  of  paralysis  soon  followed,  and  he 
died  on  December  4th.  He  was  buried  at  the  parish 
church  of  Hault  Hucknall.  The  family  and  neigh- 
bours who  attended  were  "very  handsomely  enter- 
tained with  wine,  burnt  and  raw,  cakes,  biscuits,  etc.," 
and  a  slab  of  black  marble  was  placed  upon  his 
grave.  In  the  inscription  he  is  called  "  Vir  probus  et 
fama  erudition-is domiforisque  bene  cognitus"  He  had 
amused  himself,  it  is  said,  by  allowing  his  friends  to 
prepare  epitaphs,  and  the  design  which  pleased  him  , 
most  was  a  gravestone  inscribed :  "  This  is  the  true 
Philosopher's  Stone." 

Hobbes  left  nearly  £1000,  "which,"  says  Aubrey, 
"  considering  his  charity,  was  more  than  I  expected." 
He  had  given  a  piece  of  land  to  a  nephew,  and  paid 
off  a  mortgage  of  £200  with  which  the  nephew  had 
encumbered  his  estate.  Aubrey  collects  a  few  bits  of 
information,  with  provoking  gaps,  as  to  his  appearance 
and  manners.  This  is  a  tantalising  statement  for 
phrenologists :  "  His  head  was  .  .  .  inches  in  com- 
pass (I  have  the  measure)  and  of  a  mallet  form 
(approved  by  the  physiologers)."  He  was  unhealthy 
in  youth,  but  grew  strong  when  about  forty,  and  had 
a  fresh  ruddy  complexion.  He  had  an  ample  forehead, 


64  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

and  "  yellowish-reddish  whiskers,  which  naturally 
turned  up,  a  sign  of  a  brisk  wit."  He  shaved  close, 
except  a  little  tip  under  his  lip  -  -  "  though  nature  would 
have  afforded  a  venerable  beard,"  he  abandoned  that 
ornament  to  avoid  affectation  of  philosophic  dignity. 
"  He  had  a  good  eye,  hazel  coloured,  which  would 
shine  when  he  became  eager,  as  though  there  were  a 
bright  live-coal  within  it."  Various  portraits,  one  at 
the  National  Portrait  Gallery,  and  two  in  the  rooms  of 
the  Eoyal  Society,1  show  a  head  which  is  marked  both 
by  acuteness  and  singular  dignity  of  expression. 
Hobbes  might  have  sat  for  a  portrait  of  Plato,  and  is, 
I  think,  the  best  looking  philosopher  known  to  me. 

The  following  account  of  his  habits  refers  pre- 
sumably to  his  last  years.  He  rose  about  seven,  and 
breakfasted  on  bread  and  butter,  then  he  walked  and 
meditated  till  ten,  he  dined  at  eleven,  as  his  stomach 
could  not  bear  waiting  till  the  earl's  dinner  at  two. 
After  dinner  he  took  a  pipe  of  tobacco  and  a  nap,  and 
in  the  afternoon  wrote  down  his  morning's  thoughts. 
He  had  been  much  addicted  to  music  in  his  youth,  and 
practised  on  the  bass  viol.  He  had  always  books  of 
"  prick-song  "  lying  on  his  table,  such  as  Lawes's  songs, 
and  at  night  when  he  was  in  bed,  and  the  doors  made 
fast,  so  that  he  was  sure  of  being  unheard,  he  would  sing 
aloud  for  his  health's  sake.  He  denied  the  common 
report,  that  he  was  afraid  to  be  alone  on  account  of 
.  ghosts.  He  was  not  afraid  of  spirits,  but  of  being 
knocked  on  the  head  for  five  or  ten  pounds.  Hobbes 
was  evidently  careful  about  his  health,  and  a  believer 
in  bodily  exercise.  He  played  tennis  "  twice  or  thrice 

1 A  photograph  from  one  of  the  last  is  prefixed  to  Robertson's 
monograph. 


i.]  LIFE  65 

a  year"  according  to  Aubrey  —  once  a  week  says 
Sorbiere  —  when  lie  was  well  over  seventy.  He  illus- 
trates more  than  one  argument  in  the  Leviathan  by 
reference  to  the  game.  In  the  country,  where  there 
was  no  tennis-court,  he  walked  up  and  down  hill 
till  he  was  in  a  great  sweat  and  then  had  himself 
rubbed  down.  "'Tis  not  consistent  with  an  harmon- 
ical  soul,"  as  Aubrey  observes,  "  to  be  a  woman- 
hater,  neither  had  he  an  abhorrescence  to  good  wine." 
Kennett  speaks  of  a  natural  daughter,  whom  he  called 
his  delictv.m  juventutis,  and  for  whom  he  provided.  But 
if  he  had  been  habitually  immoral,  his  respectable 
opponents  would  hardly  have  refrained,  as  they  in  fact 
did,  from  any  accusation  of  the  kind.  He  calcu- 
lated that  he  had  been  drunk  one  hundred  times  in  the 
course  of  his  life :  which,  says  Aubrey,  "  considering 
his  great  age,  did  not  amount  to  once  a  year."  The 
arithmetic  is  erroneous  ;  but  twice  a  year  would  hardly 
bring  him  up  to  the  average  of  his  time.  He  could 
never  endure  habitual  excess,  as  Aubrey  testifies,  and 
after  sixty  he  drank  no  wine.  He  had  some  more 
attacks  of  illness  (a  dangerous  one  in  1668)  besides 
those  mentioned  before,  and  his  hand  began  to  shake 
about  1650.  About  1665  his  writing  became  illegible. 
Hobbes  had  few  books  in  his  chamber;  but1 
"Homer  and  Virgil  were  commonly  on  his  table; 
sometimes  Xenophon  or  some  probable  history,  and 
Greek  Testament  or  so  "  —  which  seems  to  be  a  pretty 
good  selection.  "  He  was  wont  to  say,  that  if  he  had 
read  as  much  as  other  men,  he  should  have  known  no 
more  than  other  men."  He  appreciated,  that  is,  the 
truth  that  it  is  more  important  to  assimilate  than  to 
accumulate  materials  of  thought.  Descartes,  like 


66  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Hobbes,  insisted  upon,  and  exaggerated  his  ignorance 
of  previous  authors.  He  had  read  nothing,  as  Voltaire 
put  it,  pas  meme  VEvangile.  The  attitude  was  natural 
in  men  who  were  deliberately  rejecting  the  established 
doctrines  of  their  time,  and  trying  to  substitute  a  new 
scheme  of  thought  built  upon  entirely  new  foundations. 
The  man,  as  Kobertson  remarks,  who  began  his  career 
by  translating  Thucydides,  and  ended  it  by  translat- 
ing Homer,  cannot  be  taken  as  a  simple  contemner  of 
literature. 

Aubrey  was  properly  anxious  to  collect  some  of  his 
hero's  good  sayings.  If  he  did  not  succeed  in  making 
a  long  list,  his  fate  was  that  which  befalls  most  such 
enterprises.  He  should,  like  Boswell  or  like  Hobbes 
himself,  have  carried  a  note-book  in  his  pocket.  One 
characteristic  saying  may  be  quoted.  "He  was,"  says 
Aubrey,  "very  charitable  to  those  that  were  true 
objects  of  his  bounty.  He  gave  sixpence  one  day  to 
a  poor  beggar  in  the  Strand.  Whereupon  a  divine 
asked  him  :  '  Would  you  have  done  this  if  it  had  not 
been  Christ's  command?'  'Yea,'  said  he.  'Why?3 
quoth  the  other.  '  Because,'  said  he,  f  I  was  in  pain  to 
consider  the  miserable  condition  of  the  old  man,  and 
now  my  alms,  giving  him  some  relief,  doth  also  ease 
me.' ;  This  shows  perhaps  that  his  practice  was  better 
than  his  ethical  theory.1 

1  Hobbes  received  £50  a  year  from  his  patron  besides 
occasional  presents,  such  as  £40  for  the  dedication  of  the  De 
Corpore.  He  speaks  (in  the  life)  of  his  indifference  to  gain. 
No  avaricious  man,  he  declares,  ever  achieved  a  noble  work. 
He  had  lived  to  study,  and  he  condemns  those  who  study  for  the 
sake  of  gain.  His  boast  seems  to  be  fully  justified.  His  life 
was  worthy  of  a  philosopher,  in  spite  of  trifling  foibles,  due 
to  temper  or  timidity.  It  is  to  the  credit  of  the  British 


i.]  LIFE  67 

Before  considering  his  theories,  however,  something 
may  be  said  of  the  view  taken  of  him  by  his  contem- 
poraries. I  do  not  speak  at  present  of  the  more 
serious  antagonists  who  wrote  upon  his  philosophy. 
It  is  enough  to  say  here  that  they  attacked  him  with 
remarkable  unanimity.  His  predecessor,  Bacon,  was 
cited  on  all  sides  as  a  venerable  authority.  His 
successor,  Locke,  was  adopted  as  a  leader  by  the  great 
majority  of  the  younger  thinkers.  Hobbes  impressed 
English  thought  almost  entirely  by  rousing  opposition. 
Possibly  his  opponents  had  more  or  less  to  modify  their 
own  position  in  order  to  meet  his  arguments ;  but  to 
them  at  least  it  seemed  that  Hobbism  was  the  upas 
tree  to  be  cut  down  root  and  branch.  The  Auctariumv 
gives  a  long  list  of  contemporary  writers  upon  Hobbes ; 
but  can  only  mention  a  solitary  work  done  in  his 
defence,  and  that  anonymous.  He  was  the  typical 
atheist.  "  Atheism,"  no  doubt  was  a  name  bestowed 
upon  a  phase  of  sentiment  common  enough  at  the 
court  of  Charles  II.,  as  it  had  been,  according  to 
Mersenne,  in  Paris.  The  religious  controversies  ofj 
the  Reformation  period  had  naturally  led  to  a  "  scepti- 
cal spirit,"  such  as  found  utterance  in  Montaigne's 
immortal  essays.  The  endless  war  of  dogmas  revealed 
the  folly  of  dogmatism.  Montaigne,  though  disclaim- 
ing philosophical  pretensions,  suggested  philosophical 
problems  to  great  thinkers  like  Pascal ;  but  he  was 
acceptable  to  less  serious  minds.  The  so-called 


aristocracy  of  those  days  —  who  do  not  generally  get  many 
compliments  —  that  one  of  them  gave  to  the  hated  sceptic  a 
support  which  made  him  virtually  independent  enough  to  de- 
vote his  powers  to  philosophy,  while  he  deserved  it  hy  honourahle 
service. 


68  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

"  libertins,"  it  seems,  would  alternately  attack  and 
humble  themselves  before  the  priests,  as  they  objected 
to  any  moral  police,  or  thought  that,  after  all,  absolu- 
tion might  be  convenient.  They  could  profess  scepti- 
cism under  cover  of  more  serious  thinkers,  and  then 
make  edifying  ends  to  clear  their  scores.  Probably 
that  was  true  of  many  Hobbists.  Eachard,  best  known 
by  his  book  on  the  causes  of  the  contempt  of  the  clergy, 
wrote  in  1672  two  very  smart  dialogues  in  ridicule  of 
Hobbes.  He  divides  the  followers  of  Hobbes  into  pit, 
box,  and  gallery.  The  pit  was  filled  by  the  sturdy 
sinners  who  welcomed  him  as  an  ally  against  morality 
in  general ;  the  gallery  by  fine  gentlemen  anxious  to 
show  their  wit ;  and  the  boxes  by  men  of  gravity  and 
reputation  whose  approval  was  more  cautious.  The 
"  Hobbist "  was  generally  taken  to  be  the  shallow 
infidel,  who  still  figures  in  edifying  tracts.  The 
character  of  the  "town-gallant"  (1680)  says  that  "he 
swears  that  the  Leviathan  may  supply  all  the  lost 
leaves  of  Solomon,  though,  for  anything  that  he  has 

* 

read  himself,  it  may  be  a  treatise  on  catching  sprats. 
He  has  only  learnt  through  the  rattle  of  coffee-houses ; 
but  the  book  maintains  that  there  are  no  angels  except 
those  in  petticoats !  A  tract  of  1686  describes  the 
"  town-fop  "  as  equipped  with  three  or  four  wild  com- 
panions, "half-a-dozen  bottles  of  Burgundy,  and  two 
leaves  of  Leviathan"  In  Farquhar's  Constant  Couple. 
(1700),  the  hypocrite  pulls  out  of  his  pocket  a  book 
supposed  by  his  friends  to  be  full  of  "pious  ejacula- 
tions," while  he  remarks  to  himself :  "  This  Hobbes  is 
an  excellent  fellow."  The  only  concrete  instance  of 
such  a  Hobbist  mentioned  is  Charles  Blount  (1654-  . 
1693),  the  unfortunate  deist,  who  killed  himself  because  ' 


i.]  LIFE  69 

he  was  not  allowed  to  marry  his  deceased  wife's  sister. 
He  published  various  tracts,  including  a  sheet  of  say- 
ings from  Hobbes's  works,  and  a  tract  borrowed  from 
Milton's  Areopagitim,  and  deserved  to  be  regarded  as 
something  more  than  a  "  town-fop."  According  to 
Aubrey,  Dryden  greatly  admired  Hobbes,  and  in  his 
plays  made  use  of  some  of  THobbes's  doctrines.  I  am 
not  aware  of  any  coincidence  in  confirmation  of  this. 
Dryden  says  himself  that  he  was  sceptical  by  nature, 
and  before  his  conversion  he  may  have  sympathised 
with  Hobbes's  hatred  of  priestcraft;  but  his  poems 
on  religion  do  not  seem  to  imply  any  familiarity  with  / 
the  Leviathan.  Hobbes  ceases  about  the  end  of  the 
century  to  be  the  butt  of  all  orthodox  controversialists. 
In  the  following  generation,  Toland  and  Collins,  who 
professed  to  be  applying  Locke's  philosophy  in  the'x 
interests  of  free-thinking,  became  the  regular  objects 
for  attacks,  and  Hobbes  passes  out  of  notice.  War- 
burton,  who  loved  acute  paradox,  notices  the  change,^ 
and  speaks  of  Hobbes  with  a  certain  admiration ;  but 
he  shared  the  fate  of  all  his  contemporaries,  as  the 
eighteenth  century  came  to  think  the  seventeenth 
hopelessly  old-fashioned. 


CHAPTER   II 

THE    WORLD  1 

1.    Hoobes's  starting-point  and  aims 

I  REMARKED,  superfluously  perhaps,  that  the  circum- 
stances revealed  by  Hobbes's  biography  had  an  impor- 
tant bearing  upon  an  appreciation  of  his  philosophy. 
The  two  incidents  to  which  he  gives  a  place  in  his  own 
life,  the  sudden  revelation  of  the  charms  of  Euclid 
when  he  was  forty,  and  the  conversation  upon  the 
nature  of  sense-perception,  mark  the  impression  made 
upon  him  by  movements  in  the  contemporary  world 
of  scientific  and  philosophic  thought.  On  the  other 
side,  his  position  in  the  family  of  a  great  noble  en- 
couraged a  keen  interest  in.  the  controversies  which 
distracted  the  political  world.  His  own  intellectual 
and  moral  idiosyncrasies  of  course  determined  his  spe- 
cial attitude  towards  the  great  issues  involved  in  both 
cases.  Hobbes's  idiosyncrasies  are  sufficiently  obvious. 
He  was,  in  the  first  place,  a  born  logician.  He  loved 
reasoning  for  its  own  sake.  His  great  aim  was  to  be 
absolutely  clear,  orderly,  and  systematic.  He  desired, 

1  The  De  Corpore,  which  is  the  chief  authority  for  the  follow- 
ing chapter,  is  in  the  first  volume  of  the  Latin  works  in  Moles- 
worth's  edition.  An  English  translation,  superintended,  but  not 
written,  by  Hobbes  and  containing  some  curious  mistakes,  forms 
the  first  volume  of  the  English  works. 

70 


CHAP,  ii.]  THE  WORLD  71 

in  modern  phrase,  to  effect  the  thorough  unification  of 
knowledge.  Euclid  fascinated  him  as  constituting  a 
complete  chain  of  demonstrable  propositions,  each 
indissolubly  linked  to  its  predecessor,  and  every  one 
confirming  and  confirmed  by  the  others.  A  complete 
theory  of  things  in  general  should,  he  thought,  be  a 
philosophical  Euclid;  and  he  hoped  to  lay  down  its 
fundamental  principles  and  its  main  outlines.  He 
shrank  from  no  convictions  to  which  his  logic  appeared 
to  lead  him  ;  and  he  expounded  them  with  a  sublime 
self-confidence,  tempered,  indeed,  by  his  decided  un- 
willingness to  become  a  martyr.  Of  course,  like  most 
men  in  whom  the  logical  faculty  is  predominant,  he 
was  splendidly  one-sided.  When  things  seemed  clear 
to  him,  he  could  not  even  understand  that  any  diffi- 
culties existed  for  any  one.  That  difficulties  did  in 
fact  exist  is  plain  enough  to  his  readers,  if  only  from 
the  curious  devices  by  which  he  is  sometimes  driven 
to  meet  them.  But  though  to  others  he  may  appear 
to  be  evading  the  point,  or  adopting  inconsistent 
solutions,  to  himself  he  always  seems  to  be  following 
the  straightforward  path  of  inexorable  logic. 

One-sidedness  is  a  most  valuable  quality.  It  means 
willingness  to  try  intellectual  experiments  thoroughly. 
A  man  who  sees  the  objections  to  an  hypothesis,  is 
tempted  not  to  give  it  a  fair  trial ;  the  man  who  sees 
no  objections,  is  tempted  to  force  all  doctrine  into  his 
own  preconceived  framework ;  but,  on  the  other  hand, 
he  is  more  likely  to  bring  into  relief  whatever  truth 
it  may  really  contain.  He  may  at  times  show  that 
what  seemed  to  be  merely  paradox  is  an  important 
element  of  the  whole  truth.  More  frequently,  no 
doubt,  he  may  enable  others  to  perceive  the  precise 


72  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

points  at  which  his  system  breaks  down.  One-sided- 
ness,  it  need  hardly  be  said,  implies  defects.  Hobbes, 
for  example,  was  not  a  poet ;  he  had  no  sympathy  for 
the  imaginative  and  emotional  thinkers ;  he  would 
have  been  the  last  man  to  lose  himself,  like  his  con- 
temporary, Sir  Thomas  Browne,  in  an  0  Altitudo,  or  to 
soar  into  the  regions  in  which  the  mystic  is  at  home. 
For  him  those  regions  were  simply  the  habitat  of 
absurd  chimeras,  to  be  exorcised  by  downright  hard- 
hitting dialectics.  He  loved  to  be  in  broad  daylight, 
to  base  himself  on  the  tangible  facts  which  undoubtedly 
must  be  recognised  in  a  satisfactory  system.  Mystery 
for  him  means  nonsense,  and  is  to  be  excluded  from 
all  speculation  whether  upon  geometry  or  religion. 
Invaluable  services  are  rendered  by  the  active  appli- 
cation of  such  an  intellect;  but  clearly  its  possessor 
is  likely  to  say  a  good  many  things  which  will  shock 
people  of  a  different  turn,  and  his  want  of  sympathy 
with  their  sentiments  may  lead  him  to  dismiss  con- 
temptuously and  abruptly  opinions  which  may  conceal 
important  truth  under  vague  imagery. 

I  must  endeavour  to  set  forth  Hobbes's  main  positions 
impartially,  without  attempting  to  go  far  into  problems 
which  since  his  day  have  been  discussed  by  generations 
of  philosophers,  and  which,  I  fancy,  are  not  as  yet 
quite  settled. 

One  point  may  be  noticed  at  starting.  Hobbes 
gave  his  views  of  both  "  natural  "  and  "  civil "  philo- 
sophy, to  use  his  own  terms.  He  has  been  criticised 
both  as  a  natural  and  as  a  civil  philosopher,  and 
the  one  or  the  other  part  of  his  work  has  been  made 
most  prominent  according  to  the  special  purpose 
or  personal  taste  of  the  critic.  This  suggests  the 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  73 

inquiry,  whether  his  interest  in  physical  science  or  in 
the  nature  of  men  and  institutions  gave  the  real  start- 
ing-point of  his  speculation.  A  decisive  answer  can 
scarcely  be  given,  and  an  answer  is  of  the  less  impor- 
tance because  his  most  characteristic  point  is  precisely 
his  conviction  that  the  two  inquiries  are  inseparably 
connected.  Hobbes  appears  to  have  been  the  first 
writer  who  clearly  announced  that  "civil  philoso- 
phy" must  be  based  upon  "natural  philosophy,"  or, 
in  other  words,  that  a  sound  "sociology'  must  be 
based  upon  scientific  knowledge.  He  may  be  called 
a  Herbert  Spencer  of  the  seventeenth  century,  and 
in  spite  of  very  wide  differences,  there  is  a  certain 
resemblance  between  the  two  thinkers.  Each  of  them 
aims  at  exhibiting  a  complete  system  in  which  the  <^ 
results  of  the  physical  sciences  will  be  co-ordinated  with 
ethical  and  political  theory.  Hobbes's  attempt  was  of 
necessity  premature ;  the  essential  data  were  not  in 
existence.  Physical  science  was  still  in  its  infancy ; 
and  Hobbes's  own  scientific  knowledge  was  necessarily 
as  crude  as  that  of  his  contemporaries,  and  had  special 
defects  of  its  own.  The  political  philosophy,  again, 
however  acute,  was  stated  in  terms  of  speculations 
which  have  long  become  obsolete.  The  Leviathan, 
once  so  terrible,  may  be  taken  for  an  intellectual  fossil 
—  a  collection  of  erroneous  assumptions  and  sophistries 
w*hich  are  confuted  in  a  paragraph  or  two  of  the 
students'  text-books.  Perhaps  our  descendants  may 
be  equally  dissatisfied  with  systems  which  bulk  very 
largely  in  our  eyes,  though  we  may  hope  that  they 
will  make  allowance  for  our  inevitable  ignorance. 

If,  however,  thinkers  did  not  break  ground  by  fram- 
ing "  premature '    schemes   of  doctrine,   they  would 
y 


74  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

never  advance  to  riper  and  more  durable  schemes. 
Great  thinkers  at  least  do  something  to  test  the  solidity 
of  the  old  structures,  and  here  and  there  lay  a  founda- 
tion-stone or  two,  which  will  be  built  into  the  more 
comprehensive  edifices  of  the  future.  We  are  not 
ourselves  so  far  advanced  in  the  social  sciences  that 
we  can  afford  to  judge  our  predecessors  with  the  con- 
fidence of  men  who  have  reached  a  definitive  system. 
The  tentative  gropings  of  a  great  man,  trying  to  secure 
a  starting-point,  are  always  instructive,  and  Hobbes 
may  at  least  show  us  what  were  some  of  the  besetting 
fallacies  at  an  early  stage  of  speculation.  He  certainly 
has  such  merits  in  a  high  degree,  though,  as  I  think, 
more  decidedly  in  "civil"  than  in  "natural "  philosophy. 

Hobbes  succeeded  in  working  out  a  legal  or  political 
theory,  which  had  a  very  genuine  and  powerful  effect 
upon  the  course  of  speculation.  Few  people  accepted 
the  political  doctrine  generally  attributed  to  him,  and 
most  people  repudiated  it  with  indignation.  Still  it 
influenced  men,  if  only  by  repulsion,  while  much  of 
his  argument  has  been  adopted  by  others,  and  occasion- 
ally reappears  in  curiously  different  combinations.  I 
consider  this  to  be  the  most  important  aspect  of 
"  Hobbism."  It  may  be  said,  too,  that  whatever  was 
his  real  starting-point — whether  he  began  with  political 
opinions  and  then  tried  to  bring  them  into  connection 
with  his  scientific  views,  or  followed  the  reverse  pro- 
xjess  —  it  was  certainly  the  political  doctrine  which  he 
/  /  expounded  most  thoroughly  and  consistently.  His 
teaching,  whatever  its  faults,  has  evidently  been  traced 
out  carefully  and  patiently,  and  is  a  complete  elabora- 
tion of  certain  leading  principles. 

It  is,  however,  essential  to  consider  his  views  of 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  75 

"natural  philosophy."  He  contributed  nothing  to 
the  special  sciences.  His  expositions  of  first  principles 
show  inconsistencies  which  suggest  that  he  had  not 
considered  them  with  the  sustained  attention  which 
he  devoted  to  his  political  writing.  Nor  does  it  appear 
that  he  had  so  important  an  influence  upon  succeeding 
schools  of  thought  in  this  as  in  the  other  direction. 
But  he  at  any  rate  laid  down  in  a  most  unflinching 
and  vigorous  fashion  certain  doctrines  which,  to  say 
the  least,  startled  his  contemporaries,  and  so  far  must 
have  done  them  good.  Theologians  and  moralists 
paid  him  the  compliment  of  taking  him  for  their 
most  serious  opponent.  He  was  regarded  as  the 
type,  though  almost  a  solitary  instance,  of  inter- 
necine hostility  to  established  beliefs.  Upon  him, 
•we  may  say,  were  concentrated  the  various  anti- 
pathies which  in  the  nineteenth  century  were  pro- 
voked by  evolutionism,  agnosticism,  materialism,  and 
destructive  criticism.  That  is  to  say,  he  personified 
the  tendencies  of  thought  which  are  supposed  to 
result  from  the  study,  or  the  too  exclusive  study,  of 
the  physical  sciences.  I  express  no  opinion  as  to 
the  merits  of  the  question  involved.  Everybody 
admits  that  the  physical  sciences  embody  a  vast 
amount  of  definitively  established  truth,  and  that,  so 
far  as  they  are  true,  they  cannot  be  inconsistent  with 
any  other  truths.  The  problem  is  whether  the  alleged 
incompatibility  between  the  conclusions  of  legitimate 
science  and  those  of  the  accepted  theology  is  really 
insuperable,  or  only  appears  to  be  insuperable  when 
the  man  of  science  reads  a  false  interpretation  into 
his  doctrines. 

Now  Hobbes,  according  to   the   judgment  of  con- 


76  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

temporaries,  interpreted  the  scientific  principles  of 
his  day  in  a  sense  which  made  them  totally  irrecon- 
cilable with  orthodox  belief,  and  anticipated  with 
great  penetration  some  inferences  which  in  later 
years  have  shocked  and  alarmed  believers.  How  far 
Hobbes  himself  admitted  or  denied  this  will  appear 
presently.  In  any  case  he  represents  the  first  definite 
emergence  in  English  thought  of  an  antagonism  which 
in  later  generations  was  to  develop  and  to  acquire  an 
absorbing  interest.  The  scientific  impulse  of  the  time 
had  found  its  English  prophet  in  Bacon.  Whatever 
his  failure  in  the  attempt  to  lay  down  the  true 
scientific  method,  his  surpassing  literary  power  en- 
abled him  to  make  a  most  imposing  forecast  of  the 
coming  empire  of  man  over  nature.  The  men  who 
founded  the  Royal  Society  could  appeal  to  Bacon's 
vast  reputation  as  sanctioning  their  enterprise.  Now 
they  could  do  so  without  incurring  any  suspicion  as 
to  their  orthodoxy.  Boyle,  for  example,  one  of  the 
chief  leaders,  was  as  conspicuous  for  his  piety  as  for 
his  scientific  zeal.  There  was  nothing  objectionable 
in  the  precepts  which  direct  a  careful  and  methodical 
study  of  phenomena  in  order  to  discover  their  laws. 
"  Baconian  induction  "  implied  no  conception  either  of 
the  heterodox  or  of  the  orthodox  variety.  It  rather 
suggested  that  we  should  attend  to  facts  and  leave 
ultimate  principles  to  take  care  of  themselves.  Bacon 
denounced  the  old  scholastic  subtleties  which  had 
shown  their  futility  in  dealing  with  the  physical  sciences, 
and  by  so  doing  he  might  in  some  degree  discredit  the 
dogmatic  system  of  theology  associated  with  the  old 
philosophy.  That,  however,  so  it  seemed  to  the  more 
liberal  thinkers  of  the  time,  did  not  imply  an  attack  on 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  77 

natural  theology,  but  rather  the  need  of  disengaging 
its  truth  from  the  scholastic  logomaehfes  by  which  it 
has  been  overlaid.  The  ablest  English  divines  of  the 
next  generation  sympathised  with  that  doctrine. 

In  Hobbes  the  spirit  of  science  first  becomes 
dogmatic  and  aggressive.  He  lays  down  with  the 
utmost  calmness  and  confidence  the  most  startling 
principles.  He  thinks  them  so  reasonable  and  obvious 
that  you  might  expect  even  a  bishop  to  accept  them. 
They  are  demonstrated  once  for  all.  The  point  of 
view  from  which  he  started  is  indicated  by  his  two 
significant  anecdotes.  The  scientific  method  which 
impresses  him  is  that  of  which  Euclid  gave  him  the 
typical  instance.  It  is  a  deductive  method,  which 
develops  all  its  conclusions  from  undeniable  first 
principles.  He  scorns  the  accumulation  of  experi- 
ments. The  difficulty  which  impresses  him,  is  not 
that  we  have  not  sufficient  data,  but  that  we  do  not 
reason  upon  them  with  rigorous  accuracy.  In  the 
second  place,  the  one  universal  phenomenon  is  motion. 
We  see  things  changing  their  positions  relatively  to 
each  other,  and  in  the  last  analysis,  that  is  really  all 
that  we  can  know  or  measure./  Contemporary  develop- 
ments of  science  have  impressed  these  convictions  upon 
him.  His  view  of  them  is  sufficiently  indicated  in  the 
"  Epistle  Dedicatory  "  to  the  De  Corpore.  He  is  struck 
by  the  novelty  of  science.  The  ancients,  indeed,  had 
done  much  in  geometry,  and  left  in  it  "  a  most  perfect 
pattern  "  of  their  logic.  Astronomy  only  began  when 
Copernicus  revived  an  ancient  opinion  which  had  been 
"  strangled  by  a  snare  of  words."  Copernicus  led  to 
Galileo,  whose  discovery  was  the  "  first  that  opened 
to  us  the  gate  of  natural  knowledge  universal,  which 


78  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

is  the  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  motion."  The 
"  science  of  man's  body '  was  first  discovered  with 
"  admirable  sagacity  "  by  Harvey  —  "  the  only  man  I 
know  that,  conquering  envy,  has  established  a  new 
doctrine  in  his  lifetime."  Extraordinary  advances 
have  been  made  by  Kepler  and  by  Hobbes's  "  two 
friends,  Gassendi  and  Mersenne,"  to  whom  he  would 
have  no  doubt  added  Descartes,  had  Descartes  been 
equally  friendly.  "  Civil  philosophy  is  much  younger, 
as  being  no  older  (I  say  it  provoked,  and  that  my 
detractors  may  know  how  little  they  have  wrought 
upon  me)  than  my  own  book  De  Give.7'  "There 
walked  in  old  Greece,  indeed,  a  certain  phantasm 
for  superficial  gravity,  though  full  within  of  fraud 
and  filth,  a  little  like  philosophy ; ':  this  was  adopted 
by  the  first  doctors  of  the  Church,  who  thus  "  be- 
trayed the  citadel  of  Christianity."  Into  it  there 
entered  a  theory  called  school  divinity,  walking  on 
one  foot  firmly,  which  is  the  Holy  Scripture,  but 
halting  on  the  other  rotten  foot,  which  the  Apostle 
Paul  called  vain  and  might  have  called  pernicious 
philosophy;  for  it  has  raised  an  infinite  number  of 
controversies  in  the  Christian  world  concerning  re- 
ligion, and  from  these  controversies,  wars.  It  thus 
resembles  the  Empusa  of  the  comic  poet,  having  one 
brazen  leg,  and  the  other  the  leg  of  an  ass.  By 
putting  into  a  clear  shape  the  "  true  method  of 
natural  philosophy '  he  will  drive  away  the  meta- 
physical confusion,  "  not  by  skirmish,  but  by  letting 
in  the  light  upon  her."  The  "Empusa"  is  to  be 
exorcised  because  she  has  strangled  the  infant  science 
by  words.  But  what  we  have  to  do  is  not  to  follow 
her  through  the  monstrous  labyrinth  of  sophistry 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  79 

which  she  has  spun  over  the  world,  but  simply  to 
use  our  eyes  and  to  look  at  the  plain  facts. 

We  have  raised  a  dust,  as  Berkeley  said  afterwards, 
and  complained  that  we  cannot  see.  Philosophy  is  now 
among  men,  is  the  opening  remark  of  the  De  Corpore,  as 
corn  and  wine  were  in  the  world  in  ancient  time.  There 
were  always  vines  and  ears  of  corn ;  but  as  they  were 
not  cared  for,  men  had  to  live  upon  acorns.  So  every 
man  has  natural  reason ;  but  for  want  of  improving  it, 
most  men  have  to  be  content  with  the  acorns  of  "  daily 
experience."  They  show  sounder  judgment  than  those 
who  (like  the  schoolmen)  "  do  nothing  but  dispute  and 
wrangle  like  men  that  are  not  well  in  their  wits." 
Hobbes  proposes  to  "lay  open  the  few  and  first  ele- 
ments of  philosophy  in  general  as  so  many  seeds  from 
which  pure  and  true  philosophy  may  hereafter  spring 
up  by  little  and  little."  He  will  show  how  to  culti- 
vate the  corn  and  wine.  Science,  we  have  been  told, 
is  nothing  but  organised  common-sense.  And  Hobbes 
anticipates  this  dictum. 

Thus  Hobbes' s  method  is  to  be  that  which  has 
already  borne  fruit  in  the  hands  of  the  great  thinkers 
of  the  time.  Geometry  has  already  made  a  fresh 
start.  Copernicus  has  shown  how  the  stars  move. 
Galileo  will  enable  us  to  explain  how  each  movement 
is  determined  by  previous  movements.  The  science 
of  astronomy  will  thus  be  constituted  by  the  help  of 
geometry.  Then  Harvey's  great  discovery  suggests 
that  the  human  body  also  is  a  mechanism,  the  various 
movements  of  which  must  be  explicable  on  the  same 
principles.  The  circulation  of  the  blood,  like  the 
revolution  of  the  planets,  is  simply  a  case  of  motion ; 
and  when  we  have  the  facts  and  the  laws  of  nature, 


80  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

we  shall  be  able  to  deduce  all  physiological  pheno- 
mena, like  all  astronomical  phenomena,  by  the  help 
of  geometry.  Hobbes  assumes  also  that  the  same 
methods  will  enable  us  to  construct  his  "  civil r' 
philosophy. 

Meanwhile  we  see  the  general  impression  made 
upon  Hobbes  by  his  studies  in  Euclid,  and  by  his 
doctrine  that  motion  is  the  universal  fact.  It  means, 
in  short,  that  he  holds  that  the  aim  of  all  philosophy 
is  to  give  a  mechanical  theory  of  the  universe.  That, 
again,  is  to  say  that  he  sees  clearly  what  is  in  fact 
the  ultimate  aim  of  all  the  physical  sciences*.  The 
scientific  inquirer  endeavours  as  far  as  possible  to  give 
the  rules  embodied  in  all  physical  phenomena  in  terms 
of  time  and  space.  He  imagines  a  bewildering  dance 
of  innumerable  atoms,  lying  somehow  behind  the 
visible  world,  moving  in  different  directions,  colliding, 
combining  and  separating  and  going  through  the  most 
complicated  evolutions.  Perhaps  the  ignorant  person, 
or  the  profound  metaphysician,  may  decline  to  believe 
that  there  are  any  such  things  at  all,  or,  at  any  rate 
to  believe  that  they  are  the  only  realities.  But  even 
if  they  do  not  exist,  they  have  to  be  invented.  Our 
justification  for  creating  them  is  that  they  enable  us 
to  state  the  rules  by  which,  from  a  given  state  of 
things,  we  can  accurately  foretell  the  future  or  go 
back  to  the  past.  They  may  be  only  a  working 
hypothesis,  or  may  be  realities  which  might  con- 
ceivably become  visible  or  tangible.  The  method, 
however,  in  any  case,  implies  that  the  ultima.te 
problem  is,  as  Hobbes  said,  one  of  geometry.  The 
atoms  have  no  properties,  except  the  property  of 
embodying  certain  laws  of  motion ;  and  the  whole 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  81 

problem  becomes  that  of  stating  how  one  state  of 
motion  will  pass  into  another.  That  is  to  say,  it  is 
ultimately  a  problem  of  geometry  or  the  measurement 
of  spaces.  So  far  Hobbes  agrees  with  Descartes : 
"  Give  me  space  and  movement,  and  I  will  make 
the  world."  Toute  ma  physique  n'est  autre  chose  que  la 
geometric.  Hobbes  undoubtedly  was  not  so  good  a 
geometer  as  Descartes ;  but  they  fully  agree  in  prin- 
ciple. "  They  that  study  natural  philosophy,"  says 
Hobbes,  "  study  in  vain,  except  they  begin  at  geo- 
metry ;  and  such  writers  and  disputers  thereof  as  are 
ignorant  of  geometry  do  but  make  their  hearers  and 
readers  lose  their  time."  Civil  philosophy  must,  as  he 
adds,  be  based  upon  physics,  and  therefore  upon  geo- 
metry. Both  Hobbes  and  Descartes  accepted  Harvey's 
discovery  as  giving  a  mechanical  explanation  of  physio- 
logical phenomena.  Descartes's  doctrine  that  animals 
are  automatic  was  equally  applicable  to  the  working 
of  the  human  body,  and  Huxley  has  set  forth  with 
his  usual  vigour  and  clearness  the  importance  of  this 
doctrine  in  the  development  of  physiology. 

Upon  such  questions  I  can  say  nothing ;  and  Hobbes 
did  not  distinguish  himself  in  that  direction.  Bat  the 
next  peculiarity  of  his  philosophy  is  marked  by  his 
divergence  from  Descartes.  In  his  objections  to  the 
Meditations,  Hobbes  criticises  the  famous  "je  pense  : 
done  je  suis"  "  I  think  ';  and  "  I  am  thinking,"  he 
says,  mean  the  same.  Therefore  the  conclusion  is 
good  :  "  If  I  think,  I  am."  But  it  does  not  follow  that 
"  I "  who  think  am  a  spirit  or  a  soul.  On  the  contrary, 
he  declares,  it  would  seem  to  follow  that  a  thing  which 
thinks  is  something  corporeal.  I  do  not  think  that  I 
think,  I  simply  think ;  or  thought  and  its  object  are 

G 


82  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

one.  Descartes  complains  that  Hobbes  has  not 
attended  to  a  later  passage  in  the  Meditations,  which 
proves  that  the  soul  or  thinking  thing  cannot  be 
corporeal.  I  need  not  go  into  the  arguments.  The 
difference  is  indeed  of  that  radical  kind  in  which 
argument  rarely  produces  agreement.  Descartes  con- 
ceives himself  to  have  proved  that  the  soul  and  the 
body  are  of  diametrically  opposite  natures,  and  though 
he  believes  in  both,  thinks  that  our  conviction  of  the 
existence  of  the  soul  is  more  fundamental  than  our 
conviction  of  the  existence  of  the  body.  The  complete 
antithesis  between  the  spiritual  and  the  natural  world 
became  of  course  a  cardinal  point  of  his  system,  and 
generations  of  metaphysicians  were  to  puzzle  them- 
selves over  the  nature  of  the  intimate  relation  which, 
as  he  also  held,  binds  them  in  inseparable  unity. 

Hobbes,  on  the  other  hand,  seems  simply  to  ignore 
this  contrast.  He  takes  for  granted,  for  he  scarcely 
argues  the  question,  that  the  material  world  is  the 
only  world.  In  a  later  Objection,  he  gives  it  as  his 
own  opinion  that  spirit  is  nothing  but  a  movement 
in  certain  parts  of  the  organism.  In  other  words, 
thought,  as  well  as  every  physical  process,  is  a  species 
of  the  universal  genus  "  motion."  Hobbes  is  so  far  a 
simple  and  thoroughgoing  materialist.  That  of  course 
simplifies  things.  The  whole  of  knowledge  represents 
for  him  an  extension  of  the  physical  sciences.  The 
theory  of  the  human  body  and  the  theory  of  the 
political  body  are  more  complicated  than  the  theory  of 
the  stars ;  but  we  still  have  to  do  with  nothing  but 
motion,  though  in  forms  more  intricate  and  difficult  to 
measure.  "  The  whole  mass  of  things  that  are,"  he 
says  in  the  Leviathan,  "  is  corporeal,  that  is  to  say, 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  83 

body  ;  and  hath  the  dimensions  of  magnitude,  namely, 
length,  breadth,  and  depth ;  also  every  part  of  body  is 
likewise  body,  and  hath  the  like  dimensions ;  and  con- 
sequently every  part  of  the  universe  is  body,  and  that 
which  is  not  body  is  no  part  of  the  universe ;  and 
because  the  universe  is  all,  that  which  is  no  part  of 
it  is  nothing,  and  consequently  nowhere.  Nor  does  it 
follow  from  hence,"  he  adds,  "that  spirits  are  nothing  : 
for  they  have  dimensions  and  are  therefore  really 
bodies,  though  that  name  in  common  speech  be  given 
to  such  bodies  only  as  are  visible  and  palpable,  that  is, 
that  have  some  degree  of  opacity."  The  last  sentence  is 
required  by  a  consideration  which  frequently  hampers 
his  utterance.  He  is  bound  to  admit  that  spirits  exist, 
for  spirits  are  mentioned  in  Scripture,  and,  for  what-  ^ 
ever  reason,  he  will  not  contradict  Scripture.  But 
no  proof  can  be  given  of  existences  of  which  it  is 
impossible  to  have  "  natural  evidence."  All  evidence 
appeals  to  the  senses ;  but  a  spirit  is  taken  to  be  that 
which  does  not  "  work  upon  the  sense,"  and  is  there- 
fore not  "  conceptible."  When  we  use  such  words  as 
"  living,  sensible,  rational,  hot,  cold,  moved,  quiet,"  as 
he  calmly  remarks,  the  word  "  matter  "  or  "  body  "  is 
understood,  all  such  "  being  names  of  matter."  In 
"  natural  discourse,"  therefore,  a  "  spirit '  means  a 
phantasm  —  a  dream  mistaken  for  a  reality.  The 
spirits  mentioned  in  supernatural  discourse  must 
exist ;  they  must  therefore  be  bodies,  for  nothing 
exists  except  bodies  ;  but  they  can  be  kept  out  of 
harm's  way.  As  bodies  they  must  be  space-filling ; 
but  they  are  made  of  such  subtle  materials  that  they 
cannot  act  upon  other  bodies.  They  cannot  make 
their  existence  known,  for  they  cannot  affect  motion. 


84  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Motion  is  the  cause  of  all  things  :  "  all  mutation  is 
motion ;  motion  can  have  no  cause  except  motion ; " 
and  these  flimsy  entities  are  in  the  universe  without 
taking  part  in  it.  For  us  they  are  nonentities.  If 
motion  can  be  caused  by  motion  alone,  that  motion 
can  cause  nothing  but  motion.  Hobbes's  opponents 
inferred  that,  as  thought  is  not  motion,  it  must 
have  some  other  cause,  or  inhere  in  a  subject  which 
is  not  material.  Hobbes  infers  that  as  nothing 
can  exist  which  is  not  material,  thought  must  itself 
be  motion. 

This  is  really  Hobbes's  starting-point  and  guiding 
principle.  Man  is  an  automaton ;  thought  is  a  motion 
in  his  brain ;  all  his  actions  can  be  explained  by  the 
laws  of  motion,  like  the  motion  of  a  clock  or  of  the 
Chatsworth  waterworks.  In  the  attempt  to  carry  out 
this  conception  thoroughly,  Hobbes  gets  into  various 
difficulties.  A  modern  materialist  may  perhaps  urge 
that  the  difficulties  can  be  surmounted  by  a  fuller 
knowledge  of  physical  science.  The  opposite  explana- 
tion is  that  the  initial  assumption  is  radically  false, 
and  that  Hobbes's  merit,  as  Professor  Hoeffding  says, 
is  that  his  consistent  adoption  of  it  brings  out  the 
inevitable  failure  of  a  thoroughgoing  materialism. 

To  understand  him  we  must  begin  by  granting  his 
postulate.  Let  us  admit  provisionally  that  man  is 
simply  an  automaton  and  yet  that  he  can  somehow 
think,  feel,  reason,  and  become  a  philosopher. 

First  of  all,  however,  Hobbes  explains  what  is  the 
aim  of  his  philosophy.  Philosophy,  according  to  him, 
means  a  knowledge  of  the  effects  which  will  be  produced 
by  given  causes,  or,  conversely,  of  the  causes  which  have 
produced  given  effects.  We  may  trace  the  working  of 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  85 

the  mechanism  in  order  to  make  use  of  it  for  our  own 
purposes.  Philosophy  then  is  strictly  "  practical "  or 
"  utilitarian,"  to  use  the  common  phrases.  The  "  in- 
ward glory  and  triumph  of  niiiid''  arising  from,  our 
mastery  of  some  abstruse  question  would  not  of  itself 
repay  the  pains  necessary  to  obtain  the  result.  "  The 
end  of  knowledge  is  power : "  a  phrase  which  recalls 
Bacon's  famous  saying.1  Both  Bacon  and  Hobbes  desire 
knowledge  to  enable  men  to  rule  the  forces  of  nature. 
The  utility  of  "  natural  philosophy  "  appears  in  such 
arts  as  navigation,  architecture,  and  so  forth ;  and  we 
may  see  what  they  have  done  for  mankind  by  com- 
paring the  civilised  races  of  Europe  with  the  Americans 
and  "  those  that  live  near  the  poles."  Since  all  men,  as 
Hobbes  assumes,  have  the  same  faculties,  the  whole 
difference  is  due  to  philosophy.  "Moral  and  civil 
philosophy,"  however,  is  equally  useful,  though  its 
utility  must  be  measured  not  by  the  commodities  which 
it  gives  but  by  the  calamities  which  it  obviates.  The 
worst  of  calamities  is  war,  especially  civil  war.  From 
war  proceed  "  slaughter,  solitude,  and  the  want  of  all 
things."  All  men  know  these  to  be  evil.  Why  then 
do  wars  continue  ?  Because  men  do  not  know  the 
causes  of  war  and  peace.  Few  men,  that  is  to  say, 


!"  Knowledge  is  power,"  as  Hamilton  points  out  (D. 
Stewart's  Works,  v.  38),  is  a  running  title  in  the  Advance- 
ment of  Learning  and  may  not  be  Bacon's  own  phrase.  How- 
ever, in  the  Meditationes  Sacrae  we  may  see  in  a  theological 
context  ipsa  scientia  potestas  est :  and  this  in  the  translation 
becomes  "knowledge  itself  is  power."  See  Bacon's  Works, 
ed.  Spedding,  vii.  241,  253.  It  has  often  been  denied  that 
Bacon  used  the  words,  as  in  Bulwer's  My  Novel,  where  the 
wise  confute  a  young  man  who  has  rashly  adopted  them.  Any- 
how, as  Hamilton  says,  they  clearly  represent  Bacon's  meaning. 


86  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

have  learnt  the  "  duties  which  unite  and  keep  men  in 
peace."  Now  "the  knowledge  of  these  duties  is  moral 
philosophy."  Hobbes  thus  holds  substantially  a  doc- 
trine which  was  characteristic  of  a  later  period  and 
was  vigorously  expounded  by  Buckle.  The  growth  of 
civilisation  means  essentially  the  growth  of  knowledge. 
Knowledge  will  not  only  enable  us  to  apply  mechani- 
cal inventions,  but  will  show  the  identity  of  human 
interests  and  lead  to  the  extirpation  of  war.  Hobbes's 
view  of  the  methods  by  which  this  consummation 
was  to  be  reached  differed  materially  from  that  of  the 
Utilitarians  of  the  middle  of  the  nineteenth  century, 
but  the  general  conception  is  the  same. 

He  proceeds  to  define  the  "  subject "  of  philosophy. 
It  has  nothing  to  do  with  theology  (for  pretty  obvious 
reasons),  nor  with  the  doctrine  of  angels,  nor  of  things 
(if  such  there  be)  which  are  not  bodies,  nor  with 
revelation  which  does  not  appeal  to  reason,  nor  with 
astrology  and  other  "  divinations  which  are  not  well 
grounded  " ;  nor  with  the  doctrine  of  "  God's  worship," 
which  is  the  "  object  of  faith,  not  of  knowledge." 
Moreover  it  excludes  "  history  as  well  natural  as 
political,  though  most  useful  (nay  necessary)  to  philo- 
sophy " ;  for  such  knowledge  is  "  but  experience  or 
authority,  and  not  ratiocination."  Philosophy  deals 
exclusively  with  the  "  generation  and  properties "  of 
the  two  chief  kinds  of  bodies  —  the  natural  body,  a 
work  of  nature,  and  the  commonwealth,  the  body 
made  by  the  agreement  of  men.  "  Civil  philosophy," 
which  deals  with  the  last,  is  divisible  into  two ; 
"  ethics,"  which  deals  with  human  nature,  and 
"  politics,"  which  deals  with  men  as  citizens.  The 
treatise,  therefore,  which  gives  the  general  principles 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  87 

applicable  to  all  philosophy  is  called  De  Corpore,  since 
"  body  "  includes  all  that  is  knowable. 


2.   Logic 

The  world  is  made  of  unchangeable  but  moving 
bodies.  All  that  happens  is  the  transformation  of  one 
set  of  motions  into  another  according  to  certain  fixed 
laws.  Somehow  or  another  we  can  ascertain  these 
laws,  and,  when  duly  systematised,  they  become  "phi- 
losophy," or  a  statement  of  necessary  truths.  What 
then  is  truth  ?  Hobbes  observes  that  "  truth  is  not  an 
affection  of  the  thing,  but  of  the  proposition  concern- 
ing it."  The  word  "  true  "  is  often,  but  inaccurately, 
opposed  to  "  feigned.'7  But,  properly  speaking,  if  we 
say  that  a  ghost  or  the  image  in  a  mirror  is  not  a  man, 
we  do  not  assert  that  the  ghost  is  "  false,"  but  that  the 
proposition  "  a  ghost  is  a  man  "  is  false.  "  A  ghost  is 
(still)  a  very  ghost."  Truth  and  falsehood  belong  to 
the  reasoning  process  which  is  peculiar  to  man,  upon 
whom  it  confers  the  privilege  of  framing  "  general 
rules."  This  privilege,  indeed,  is  "  allayed  by 
another  " ;  and  that  is  by  the  privilege  of  absurdity, 
to  which  no  living  creature  is  subject  but  man  only. 
And  of  men  "those  are  of  all  most  subject  to  it  that 
profess  philosophy."  Nothing,  as  Cicero  said,  can  be 
so  absurd  as  not  to  be  found  in  their  books.  Hobbes 
will  explain  the  source  of  their  errors. 

Meanwhile  we  have  a  problem.  Eeality  belongs  to 
bodies  ;  truth  to  propositions  or  thought.  What  then 
is  that  which  thinks  ?  Hobbes  has  replied  that  it  is 
body,  and  thought  is  a  movement  in  the  body.  But  it 
is  plain  that  if  this  be  true,  the  thinking  thing  does 


88  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

not  directly  perceive  its  own  nature.  Thought  does 
not  present  itself  as  a  movement.  We  are  not  con- 
scious of  the  physical  processes  which  somehow  con- 
stitute or  underlie  the  thinking  process.  It  follows 
that  as  thoughts  are  not  bodies,  they  are  unreal  —  mere 
nonentities  or  "  phantasms/'  as  Hobbes  generally  puts 
it.  Reality  thus  seems  to  be  entirely  divorced  from 
truth.  The  thought-process  may  be  determined  by 
motion ,  but,  as  immediately  known,  it  is  a  set  of 
imaginary  phantasmagoria  playing  over  the  surface  of 
things  but  itself  unreal.  The  "  soul ';  is  real  in  so 
far  as  it  is  material ;  but  the  ideal  world  made  of 
phantasms  is  unreal.  Yet  somehow  the  soul  manages 
to  reason  by  help  of  the  phantasms,  and  to  discover 
the  rules  of  bodily  movement.  The  problem  remains, 
how  this  process  is  to  be  explained.  Hobbes's  answer 
gives  his  theory  of  logic,  and  forms  the  first  part  of  the 
De  Corpore.  The  title  Computatio  sive  Logica  indicates 
his  peculiar  view.  All  ratiocination,  he  declares,  is 
computing.  Reasoning  is  addition  or  subtraction. 
Arithmeticians  add  or  subtract  numbers ;  geome- 
tricians add  lines  and  figures ;  logicians  add  names  to 
make  affirmations ;  affirmations  to  make  syllogisms  ; 
and  syllogisms  to  make  demonstrations.  The  type  of 
reasoning  for  him  is  still  Euclid.  Adding  and  sub- 
tracting suggest  the  process  by  which  the  square  on 
the  hypothenuse  in  his  favourite  proposition  may  be 
cut  up  and  put  together  again  so  as  to  form  the 
squares  on  the  two  sides.  He  had  a  prejudice  against 
the  new  methods  by  which  algebraic  calculation  was 
being  substituted  for  the  direct  intuitive  methods  of 
geometry,  and  to  the  arithmetic  which,  in  the  hands 
of  the  detestable  Wallis  and  his  like,  was  leading  to 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  89 

humbug  about  infinitesimals.  Arithmetic,  however, 
seems  best  to  illustrate  his  view.  Number,  as  he 
would  say,  is  not  "an  affection  of  the  thing."  The 
same  thing  may  be  one  or  twelve,  as  we  count  in  feet 
or  inches.  The  unit  is  arbitrary.  And  yet  number- 
ing enables  us  to  state  the  most  essential  properties  of 
things.  Ten  or  a  hundred  by  itself  is  a  mark  of  no 
particular  body,  and  is  therefore  a  nonentity.  But  it 
meant  something  very  real  that  Hobbes's  hundred  a 
year  came  to  just  ten  times  ten  pounds.  Reasoning 
in  general  is  counting  with  names  or  numbers. 
"  Words,"  as  he  says,  in  one  of  his  pithiest  aphorisms, 
"  are  wise  men's  counters ;  they  do  but  reckon  with 
them,  but  they  are  the  money  of  fools."  The  remark 
has  a  wide  application  ;  and,  in  this  case,  the  "  fools  ' 
are  those  who  talk  scholastic  jargon.  But  it  states 
his  general  principle.  The  "  use  of  names  in  register- 
ing our  thoughts,"  as  he  remarks  elsewhere,  "is  in 
nothing  so  evident  as  in  numbering."  Once  men 
could  not  count,  except  on  their  fingers,  as  is  shown 
by  the  decimal  notation.  The  names  learnt  in  the 
right  order  enable  us  to  perform  all  the  operations  of 
arithmetic. 

Since  the  names  are  thus  the  counters,  out  of  which 
we  frame  propositions,  we  have  to  ask  wrhat  is  a 
name  ?  Hobbes  gives  a  famous  definition.  "A  name 
is  a  word  taken  at  pleasure,  to  serve  for  a  mark  which 
may  raise  in  our  mind  a  thought  like  to  some  thought 
we  had  before,  and  which  being  (disposed  in  speech 
and *)  pronounced  to  others,  may  be  a  sign  to  them  of 
what  the  speaker  had  or  had  not  before  in  his  mind." 
Names  are  thus  "  marks  to  ourselves."  "  How  incon- 
1  Omitted  by  error  in  the  English  version. 


00  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

stant  and  fading  men's  thoughts  are,  and  how  much 
the  recovery  of  them  depends  upon  chance,  there  is 
none  but  knows  by  infallible  experience  in  himself ! ' 
No  man  remembers  numbers  without  the  names  of 
numbers  disposed  in  order  and  learnt  by  heart.  The 
name  recalls  not  only  the  thing  but  the  general  rule. 
The  results  given  by  reasoning  without  such  helps 
will  presently  slip  from  us.  We  should  get  on  very 
slowly  if  we  had  to  find  out  the  multiplication  table 
every  time  we  did  a  sum.  "  Marks  "  are  thus  neces- 
sary to  recall  thoughts,  and  become  "  signs  "  when  we 
teach  them  to  others,  which  is  an  essential  condition 
of  the  preservation  and  growth  of  science.  To  serve 
as  signs,  again,  it  is  necessary  that  names  as  marks 
should  be  "  disposed  and  ordered  in  speech."  To 
speak  rationally,  you  must  not  only  renew  the  memory 
of  a  thing,  but  say  what  you  are  thinking  of  its  rela- 
tion to  other  things.  For  that  purpose,  again,  words 
may  be  useful  which  are  not  names  of  things,  but  only 
of  "  fictions  and  phantasms  of  things."  That  words  are 
an  essential  instrument  of  thought  which,  without 
them,  could  not,  to  say  the  least,  get  beyond  rudi- 
mentary and  vague  inferences  is,  I  take  it,  a  very 
sound  doctrine.  Hobbes  did  good  service  by  directing 
attention  emphatically  to  it.  He  managed,  however, 
to  give  it  a  strange  twist.  Signs,  he  remarks,  may  be 
"  natural '  or  "  arbitrary."  The  cloud  is  a  natural 
sign  of  rain ;  a  bush  at  a  tavern  door  is  an  arbitrary 
sign  of  wine  to  be  sold.  Now  words  are  clearly 
"  arbitrary,"  as  was  signally  proved  in  the  Garden 
of  Eden,  and  again,  at  the  Tower  of  Babel.  This 
is  of  course  obvious.  If  "  homo r  meant  in  Latin 
what  "man"  means  in  English,  it  is  plain  that  the 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  91 

sound  employed  as  a  mark  varies  "arbitrarily."  But 
Hobbes  sometimes  speaks  as  if,  because  language  is 
the  instrument  of  reasoning,  and  yet  uses  arbitrary 
marks,  reasoning  gives  arbitrary  results.  So,  he  says 
in  his  fourth  objection  to  Descartes,  reasoning 
may  be  simply  an  assemblage  and  concatenation  of 
names  by  the  word  "is."1  If  that  be  so,  he  says, 
reason  does  not  conclude  to  the  nature  of  things,  but 
only  to  their  names ;  that  is,  it  shows  whether  we  are 
connecting  them  according  to  the  conventions  which 
we  have  made  at  fancy  about  their  significations. 
Descartes  naturally  replies  that  we  reason  about 
things,  not  names;  and  that  a  Frenchman  and  a 
German  may  have  the  same  thoughts  though  they 
express  them  in  entirely  different  words.  Three  and 
two,  says  Hobbes  elsewhere,  make  five,  because  men 
have  agreed  that  "five"  shall  be  the  name  of  as  many 
units  as  there  are  in  three  and  two.  That  explains 
why  we  say  "  two  "  and  "  three  ';  instead  of  "  deux  " 
and  "  trois,"  but  does  not  prove  that  we  can  alter  the 
truth  expressed  by  arbitrary  sounds.  Definitions  are 
"  truths  constituted  arbitrarily  by  the  inventors  of 
speech,  and  therefore  not  to  be  demonstrated."  We 
make  such  truths  ourselves  (vera  esse  facimus  nosmet 
i2)si)  by  our  consent  to  the  use  of  names. 

The  doctrine,  so  stated,  seems  too  absurd  even  for  a 
philosopher  (as  Hobbes  would  have  said),  and  certainly 
does  not  correspond  to  his  own  conviction  of  the  in- 
fallibility of  his  demonstrations.  It  is  inconsistent  too 

1  He  is  careful  to  point  out  that  the  copula  is  not  necessary, 
and  that  the  meaning  might  he  expressed  hy  simply  putting 
two  names  together.  A  mistake  on  this  point  leads  to  the  inven- 
tion of  such  scholastic  terms  as  "  entity." 


92  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

with  much  that  he  says  elsewhere.  It  seems  to  be  a 
trick  played  upon  him  by  his  logic,  for  trying  to  give 
a  fall  to  his  antagonists  he  loses  his  own  balance.  His 
general  line  of  thought  is  intelligible.  Philosophy,  we 
see,  according  to  him,  is  formed  by  a  chain  of  true 
propositions,  linked  or  (as  he  puts  it)  added  together. 
Each  link  is  a  syllogism ;  and  reasoning  demonstrates 
that,  if  the  first  propositions  be  true,  all  the  dependent 
propositions  must  be  equally  true.  Language  is  the 
essential  instrument  of  the  process,  though  language, 
as  he  admits,  is  not  necessary  to  thought,  only  to  the 
articulate  thought  which  leads  to  science.  We  make 
inferences  from  "  natural  signs  "  ;  rain,  for  example,  is 
suggested  by  clouds,  though  the  inference  is  often 
erroneous,  and  no  experience  can  be  demonstrative. 
Again,  a  man  though  deaf  and  dumb  may  observe 
that  the  angles  of  a  particular  triangle  are  equal  to 
two  right  angles ;  but  only  the  man  who  has  the  use 
of  speech  can  prove  that  the  property  is  necessarily 
true  of  all  triangles.  "  Experience  concludeth  nothing 
universally."  It  tells  us  that  day  and  night  have 
always  followed  each  other ;  not  that  they  always  will 
follow. 

Now,  though  "  experience r  suggests  a  kind  of 
reasoning,  it  is  only  with  the  use  of  language  that 
"  ratiocination ';  properly  begins.  Science  embodies 
"  ratiocination."  The  validity  of  ratiocination  depends 
entirely  upon  the  correct  use  of  its  essential  instru- 
ment, language.  This,  as  Hobbes  expresses  it,  means 
that  the  whole  process  is  dependent  upon  definitions. 
If  definitions  were  arbitrary,  all  science  must  be 
arbitrary.  Nothing  could  be  further  from  his  mind 
than  this  conclusion,  and  what  he  really  means  may 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  93 

be  gathered  from  the  purpose  of  his  argument. 
Philosophy  aims  first  at  deducing  effects  from  causes. 
Definitions  are  "the  primary  propositions'"  from 
which  this  process  starts.  The  definitions,  therefore, 
of  "  all  things  that  are  caused,  must  consist  of  such 
names  as  express  the  cause  or  matter  of  generation." 
When  we  have  defined  the  circle  as  the  figure  made 
by  "  the  circumduction  of  a  body  whereof  one  end 
remains  unmoved,"  we  can  deduce  all  the  properties 
of  the  circle.  Geometrical  relations  enable  us  to 
determine  the  motions  of  the  body,  and  therefore  the 
relations  of  cause  and  effect.  Theories  of  motion,  of 
"  physics,"  and  ultimately  of  ethics  and  politics,  are 
founded  upon  geometry,  and  geometry  itself  follows 
from  the  definitions.  Euclid,  it  is  true,  lays  down 
certain  axioms,  but  Hobbes  argues  that  the  axioms 
themselves  follow  from  the  definitions.  He  deduces 
the  axiom,  for  example,  that  "  a  whole  is  greater  than 
any  part  thereof '  from  the  definition  of  "  greater." 
Demonstration  requires  ratiocination,  and  ratiocination  N 
is  only  possible  when  we  start  from  definitions  which  \ 
are  "  nothing  but  the  explication  of  our  simple  con-  / 
ceptions."  The  "principles  of  ratiocination  consist  in 
our  own  understanding,  that  is,  in  the  legitimate  use 
of  such  words  as  we  ourselves  constitute."  The 
meaning  seems  to  be  that  geometrical  truths  owe 
their  peculiar  certainty  to  the  fact  that  geometry  is 
through  and  through  an  intellectual  construction. 
We  can  understand  it,  because  in  some  sense  we  make 
it.  The  definitions,  then,  are  not  "  arbitrary  "  in  the 
sense  that  any  other  combination  of  words  would  do 
as  well,  or  that  the  properties  of  a  figure  would  alter 
if  we  defined  it  differently.  By  "  arbitrary  "  he  means 


9i  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

rather  "  artificial,"  or  somehow  made  by  us  and  not 
by  the  things.  The  words  are  mere  counters,  or 
instruments  for  calculating  which  we  devise  for  the 
purpose.  We  make  them  as  a  workman  makes  keys 
for  opening  locks.  He  may  make  what  tools  he 
pleases,  but  it  does  not  follow  that  they  will  serve  his 
purpose  equally  well.  We  make  the  key  ourselves, 
but  all  keys  will  not  open  the  lock. 

We  may  define  a  figure  by  any  of  the  properties 
peculiar  to  it ;  we  may  regard  a  circle  as  made  by  the 
revolution  of  the  radius  or  as  the  figure  which  will 
enclose  the  maximum  area  by  its  circumference.  But 
we  must  somehow  find  the  mode  which  will  actually 
generate  it.  The  definition  marks  the  point  at  which 
we  have  got  hold  of  the  thing  by  its  right  end,  or  have 
so  organised  our  "  simple  conceptions  ':  that  they  ex- 
plain the  "  generation  '  of  the  more  complex.  The 
mind  must  find  the  appropriate  instruments,  though 
when  Hobbes  thinks  of  them  as  of  simple  creations  out 
of  nothing,  he  uses  "  arbitrary  "  in  an  apparently  absurd 
sense.  His  theory  thus  becomes  feasible,  and  suggests 
a  real  answer  to  the  problem  as  to  the  special  pre- 
rogative of  mathematical  proof.  How  far  it  contains 
truth  is  a  question  which  I  must  leave  to  writers  who 
can  walk  confidently  in  the  perplexing  border  region 
between  mathematics  and  metaphysics.1 

1  One  remark  may  be  made  parenthetically.  Dugald  Stewart, 
in  a  passage  which  had  a  great  effect  upon  J.  S.  Mill  (as  Mill 
tells  us  in  his  autobiography),  takes  Hobbes's  view  of  definitions 
in  geometry.  Definitions  serve  generally  to  prevent  ambiguity, 
and  in  geometry  they  serve  as  the  real  principles  of  our  reason- 
ing. He  then  remarks  that  Condillac  has  said  that  propositions, 
equations,  and  judgments  are  at  bottom  the  same  thing.  This 
he  ridicules,  observing  that  Coudillac  would  be  surprised  to 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  95 

To  complete  our  sketch  of  his  logical  scheme  we 
must  glance  at  the  process  by  which  we  get  from  the 
definitions  to  the  demonstrated  truths.  Names  are  put 
together  to  form  propositions  and  propositions  to  form 
syllogisms.  Hobbes  accepts  the  ordinary  rules  about 
syllogisms,  of  which  he  gives  a  brief  summary.  The 
question  remains  what,  according  to  him,  is  the 
ultimate  nature  of  the  process.  Why  is  the  syllogism 
demonstrative  ?  Now,  in  the  first  place,  as  a  thorough 
nominalist,  he  denies  the  existence  of  any  "  universals  ': 
except  names.  Man  is  the  name  of  Peter,  John,  and 
so  forth,  but  there  is  no  such  thing  as  an  universal 
man.  We  have  an  "  idea  "  of  one  man,  for  every  idea 
is  one  and  of  one  thing.  There  is  no  "  idea  "  of  man. 
in  general,  and  the  mistake  arises  from  supposing  that 
what  is  true  of  the  name  is  true  of  the  idea.  In 
"  nature,"  that  is,  there  are  only  individuals,  not  classes. 
Now  in  the  syllogism  we  seem  to  learn  something  from 
referring  the  individual  to  a  class.  Since  Peter  is  a 
man,  he  has  the  properties  of  a  man.  What,  then,  is 
the  implied  logic  ?  Hobbes's  answer  is  simple.  A 
proposition  is  true  "  when  the  predicate  is  the  name  of 
everything  of  which  the  subject  is  the  name."  "Man 
is  a  living  creature,"  is  true,  "because  everything 
that  is  called  man  is  also  called  living  creature."  The 
syllogism  carries  us  a  step  further  by  "  adding "  an 

find  that  he  was  reviving  the  "  obsolete  conceit >:I  of  an  old 
English  writer,  i.e.,  Hobbes.  Evidently,  the  De  Corpore  had 
fallen  into  oblivion  in  Britain,  though  in  Stewart's  time,  if 
not  in  Condillac's,  it  was  exciting  great  interest  in  France. 
Stewart  himself,  it  would  seem,  had  hardly  got  beyond  the  first 
chapter,  or  he  certainly  would  have  been  candid  enough  to 
mention  that  he  too  was  reviving  a  doctrine  of  the  old 
writer. 


96  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

affirmation.  Take,  for  example,  "  every  living  creature 
is  a  body ;  man  is  a  living  creature ;  therefore  man 
is  a  body."  The  minor  premise  is  true,  if  the  predi- 
cate "  living  creature ':  is  a  name  of  the  same  thing 
as  the  subject  (man).  The  major  premise  is  true  if 
the  predicate  (body)  is  a  name  of  the  same  thing  as  the 
subject  (living  creature).  Therefore  "  the  three  names 
are  also  names  of  the  one  and  the  same  thing,"  or 
"  man  is  a  body  "  is  a  true  proposition.  He  goes  on  to 
explain  what  "  passes  in  the  mind  "  when  we  syllogise. 
We  "  conceive  the  image  of  a  man  speaking ':  and 
remember  that  "  what  so  appears  is  called  man  "  ;  we 
have  the  image  of  the  same  man  moving,  and  remember 
that  what  so  appears  is  called  "  living  creature  " ;  and 
finally  the  image  "  filling  space ';  is  called  "  body." 
Thus  the  three  names  are  names  of  the  same  things. 
Hobbes  has  told  us  before  that  the  proposition  "  man  is 
a  living  creature ';  is  true  because  it  pleased  man  to 
impose  both  these  names  on  "  one  thing,"  and  declares 
that  the  truth  is  therefore  "  arbitrary." 

This  queer  doctrine  still  entangles  him.  If  we  only 
call  a  thing  a  "  man '  which  we  also  call  a  "  living 
creature,"  the  proposition  "  man  is  a  living  creature  " 
must  be  verbally  true.  We  have  agreed  to  put  a  mark 
only  where  there  is  another  mark.  But  that  does  not 
explain  why  "  man '  applies  to  John,  Thomas,  and 
Peter,  not  to  a  stick  or  a  dog,  nor  what  is  meant  by 
calling  these  three  men  "  living  creatures."  Hobbes's 
account  of  what  passes  in  the  mind  implies  indeed 
that  the  words  are  in  some  way  defined.  WTe  call 
that  "  man  "  which  has  the  faculty  of  speech,  and  that 
"  living  creature ';  which  moves ;  and  possibly  by 
remembering  Hobbes's  doctrine  as  to  definitions  we 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  97 

may  attribute  to  him  a  more  rational  meaning.  He  is 
always  thinking  of  his  Euclid.  The  definition  of  a 
circle  tells  us  how  it  is  generated,  and  enables  us  to 
deduce  all  its  properties,  or  to  infer  that  a  figure  which 
has  one  property  has  also  the  others.  The  different 
names  describing  the  properties  apply  to  the  same 
thing,  though  the  "thing"  is  not  a  mere  simple  unit 
but  a  complex  of  relations.  If  then  "  man ';  and 
"  living  creature ';  are  modifications  of  "  body,"  and 
if  we  could  tell  how  they  are  "  generated ';  in  con- 
formity with  certain  laws  of  motion  and  of  various 
combinations  of  matter,  we  could  deduce  all  the  pro- 
perties of  the  species  from  simple  definitions,  and  see 
how  one  attribute  such  as  "speaking"  was  a  product 
under  certain  conditions  of  "moving"  or  "living." 
The  premises  of  the  syllogism  would  express  the  rela- 
tions between  the  various  classes  thus  formed.  The 
whole  proceeding  is  for  Hobbes  "arbitrary,"  because 
the  process  is  carried  out  in  the  world  of  "  ideas  "  or 
"  phantasms  "  which  we  make  or  organise  for  ourselves 
—  for  thoughts  are  not  "things,"  but  unreal  entities, 
which  for  some  reasons  that  he  has  not  explained, 
correspond  in  some  way  to  the  facts.  Moreover,  in 
the  case  of  'l  syllogising,"  we  come  to  a  difficulty  of 
which  he  will,  as  we  shall  see,  try  to  find  some  solution. 
A  phenomenon  is  presented  to  us  in  the  concrete,  and 
we  do  not  know  the  underlying  process  by  which  it 
has  been  evolved  out  of  the  simpler  elements.  We 
cannot  in  the  least  say  how  faculty  of  speech  is  related 
to  life  in  general.  We  can  only  say  that  somehow  or 
other,  one  thing  or  one  name  includes  the  other :  and 
that  appears  to  be  an  "  arbitrary  "  assumption  made  to 
enable  us  to  reason. 

H 


98  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

3.   Physical  Science 

Whatever  is  the  explanation  of  Hobbes's  strange 
assumption  that  names  must  be  "arbitrary'  in  order 
that  reasoning  may  be  demonstrative,  we  have  the  old 
difficulty.  Certainty  belongs  to  the  world  of  thought; 
but  thought  is  "  unreal "  and  the  words  which  are  its 
tools  can  be  put  together  at  pleasure.  Keality  belongs 
to  fact  which  is  hidden  behind  the  phantasms.  How 
do  we  get  across  the  chasm  which  divides  them  ? 
What  are  the  "  things ';  which  lie  behind  the  veil 
of  thoughts  ?  This  leads  to  a  further  speculation. 
Hobbes  tells  us  that  the  things  to  which  we  give  names 
are  of  four  kinds  :  bodies,  phantasms,  "  accidents,"  and 
names  themselves.  I  need  say  nothing  of  the  "  acci- 
dents," an  irrelevant  intrusion  which  bothers  him  a 
good  deal.  The  real  distinction  is  between  bodies  and 
phantasms,  and  the  question  is  how  they  are  related. 

Here  we  come  to  a  remarkable  result.  Hobbes  seems 
to  be  diverging  from  his  thoroughgoing  materialism. 
Geometry  and  the  laws  of  motion  will  not  be  sufficient 
for  the  problems  that  meet  him.  Having  expounded 
his  logic,  he  comes  in  the  second  part  of  the  De  Cor- 
liore  to  the  first  grounds  of  philosophy.  It  is  rather 
startling  to  find  this  rigid  materialist  declaring  that 
time  and  space  are,  as  we  now  say,  "subjective." 
Descartes  begins  by  doubting  whether  our  sensations 
really  prove  the  existence  of  an  external  world,  and 
finds  doubt  insuperable.  Hobbes  begins  by  asking 
what  would  happen  if  we  supposed  the  whole  external 
world  to  be  annihilated.  He  answers  that  it  would 
make  no  difference.  We  should  still  have  our  "  ideas 
of  the  world.7'  They  are  mere  "phantasms,  happen- 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  99 

ing  internally  to  him  that  imagineth,"  but  will  still 
appear  to  be  "  external  "  and  independent  of  the  mind. 
Moreover,  even  if  outside  things  are  taken  to  remain, 
"  we  still  compute  nothing  but  our  own  phantasms." 
We  mark  out  our  measurements  of  the  stars  and  the 
earth  "  sitting  still  in  our  closets  or  in  the  dark." 
Space  is  not  an  affection  of  the  body.  Otherwise  when 
a  body  moved,  it  would  carry  its  place  away  with  it. 
Time  is  equally  a  phantasm.  A  year  is  time,  and  yet 
nobody  thinks  that  a  year  is,  "  the  accident  or  affection 
of  any  body."  The  past  and  future  do  not  exist,  and 
consequently  days,  months,  and  years  must  be  "the 
names  of  computations  made  in  our  minds."  He 
therefore  defines  space  as  the  "  phantasm  of  a  thing 
existing  without  the  mind  simply,"  and  time  as  "  the 
phantasm  of  before  and  after  in  motion."  When  space 
and  time  are  thus  declared  to  be  mere  "  phantasms," 
and  therefore  to  have  no  existence  outside  of  the 
mind,  and  when,  moreover,  we  are  told  that  our  reason- 
ing depends  entirely  upon  them,  we  are  well  on  the  way 
to  Berkeley's  idealism  or  Hume's  scepticism.  "  Phan- 
tasms "  or  "  ideas  "  — he  uses  both  words  —  are  the  ulti- 
mate elements  of  our  thoughts ;  and  it  would  be  the 
next  step  to  declare  with  Berkeley  the  non-existence  of 
matter,  wrhile  Hobbes  already  agrees  with  Hume  that  a 
soul  is  a  superfluity.  With  Hobbes,  however,  body,  it 
appears,  is  still  the  reality  and  the  only  reality.  Space, 
he  has  told  us,  is  "imaginary  because  a  mere  phantasm, 
yet  that  very  thing  which  all  men  call  so."  Now  sup- 
pose the  thing  previously  annihilated  to  be  created 
over  again.  Then  it  must,  in  the  first  place,  fill  some 
part  of  the  imaginary  space  and,  in  the  second  place, 
must  have  "  no  dependence  upon  our  thought." 


100  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Hence  he  defines  body  to  be  "  that  which  having  no 
dependence  upon  our  thought  is  coincident  or  co- 
extended  with  some  part  of  space."  A  body,  he  tells  us 
afterwards,  has  "  always  the  same  magnitude,  but  does 
not  keep  the  same  place."  "  Place  is  nothing  out  of 
the  mind,  nor  magnitude  anything  within  it."  "  Place 
is  feigned  extension,  but  magnitude  true  extension." 
Place  is  immovable,  whereas  bodies  move.  It  appears, 
therefore,  that  there  is  real  space  by  which  the 
magnitude  of  any  body  is  measured,  and  space  is  imag- 
inary. It  must,  so  it  seems,  be  both  purely  objective 
and  purely  subjective.  Though  the  phantasm  is  unreal, 
it  somehow  enables  us  to  know  the  realities. 

The  peculiarity  of  Hobbes's  position  is  just  this, 
that  he  does  not  perceive  that  any  problem  is 
raised  by  the  contrast  between  soul  and  body  —  the 
world  of  thought  and  the  world  of  things.  He  does 
not  seek  for  any  hypothesis,  such  as  Spinoza's 
one  substance  with  infinite  attributes,  intended  to 
bring  the  two  worlds  into  unity.  Bodies  are  still 
independent  of  thought,  and  are  the  sole  and 
absolute  realities.  Thought  is  a  mere  play  of  phan- 
tasms, which  are  unreal  because  only  in  the  mind. 
Yet  the  phantasms  give  us  knowledge  of  the  bodies 
which  go  on  placidly  moving  outside  of  thought ;  and 
the  mind,  which  knows  only  its  phantasms,  is  aware 
of  the  outside  world,  and  is  itself  a  set  of  motions  in 
that  world.  That,  it  seems,  must  be  simply  taken  for 
granted  and  no  explanation  is  required.  It  never 
suggests  any  scepticism  as  to  the  possibility  of  know- 
ledge. Hobbes  will  be  as  dogmatic  as  if  no  difficulty 
existed.  Nobody,  as  is  already  sufficiently  evident, 
could  be  more  profoundly  impressed  by  that  conception 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  101 


of  the  universe  which,  is  indicated  by  such  phrases  as 
the  "reign  of  law"  and  the  "uniformity  of  nature." 
All  phenomena  without  exception  present  themselves 
in  conformity  with  certain  general  rules.  The  future 
could  be  absolutely  foreseen  and  the  past  recalled  if 
we  had  the  required  knowledge.  From  the  existing 
state  of  the  solar  system,  the  astronomer  could  say 
what  it  was  at  any  preceding,  or  what  it  will  be  at  any 
succeeding  epoch.  These  powers  indeed  are  limited 
by  the  enormous  complexity  of  the  calculations  and  of 
the  facts  to  which  they  are  applied.  Other  sciences  are 
less  perfect  because  they  have  to  deal  with  more  intri- 
cate problems,  but  not  because  any  science  includes 
a  really  arbitrary  element.  From  the  minutest  to 
the  most  universal  phenomenon,  everything  that  will 
happen  is  already  predetermined.  The  fall  of  a  leaf 
or  the  explosion  of  a  world  is  equally  part  of  the 
single  unalterable  system  of  things.  Spinoza  was  to 
give  the  most  impressive  version  of  a  theory  which 
may  be  appalling  to  some  minds,  and  simply  self- 
evident  to  others  ;  but  Hobbes  was  not  less  possessed 
with  the  conviction  than  his  greater  follower. 

This  mode  of  interpreting  the  universe  is  implied  by 
the  theory  of  cause  and  effect  which  he  now  expounds. 
As  we  have  sufficiently  seen,  "  all  mutation  is  motion," 
and  the  changes  of  motion  are  simply  the  modification 
of  previous  motions.  Cause,  he  says,  is  the  aggregate 
of  all  the  accidents  of  the  agent  and  the  patient.  Omit- 
ting his  technical  word  "accident,"  we  may  say  that 
whatever  motion  takes  place  in  a  thing,  is  determined 
by  the  whole  set  of  previous  conditions.  If  all  the 
conditions  necessary  for  a  given  effect  are  present,  it 
will  "  necessarily '  happen ;  and  if  one  of  them  be 


102  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

absent,  it  will  necessarily  not  happen.  Whatever 
happens  has  a  "  necessary  cause,"  looking  backwards, 
and  looking  forwards  a  necessary  effect.  "  Causation 
and  the  production  of  effects,"  he  adds,  "  consist  in  a 
certain  continual  progress."  Causation,  that  is,  is  not 
with  him  a  mere  sequence  of  disconnected  phenomena, 
but  a  continuous  process,  in  which  one  set  of  motions 
is  always  being  transformed  into  another.  We  may 
"in  imagination"  divide  the  process  into  two  parts  at 
any  assumed  instant ;  we  shall  then  call  the  preceding 
part  the  cause,  and  the  succeeding  part  the  effect. 
The  same  causes  will  of  course  always  produce  the 
same  effect,  since  they  differ  in  nothing  but  time. 
The  conception  of  power  again  suggests  different  ways 
of  looking  at  the  same  process.  The  "power  of  the 
agent '•  is  what  is  called  the  "  efficient  cause."  We 
use  the  word  "  power  "  when  we  are  thinking  of  the 
future,  and  "  cause  '  when  we  are  thinking  of  the 
effect  as  already  produced.  The  power  of  the  patient, 
again,  is  what  is  called  the  "material  cause,"  with 
reference  to  the  effect  which  will  be  produced  by  the 
"efficient  cause,"  and  both  together  are  the  entire 
cause.  Besides  these  the  traditional  scheme  recognised 
also  "formal'  and  "final7  causes.  The  "formal," 
according  to  Hobbes,  are  superfluous.  "  When  it  is  said 
that  the  essence  of  a  thing  is  the  cause  thereof,  as 
to  be  rational  is  the  cause  of  man,  it  is  not  intelligible ; 
for  it  is  all  one  as  if  it  were  said,  to  be  a  man  is  the 
cause  of  man,  which  is  not  well  said."  A  "  final  cause," 
again,  "has  no  place  but  in  such  things  as  have  sense 
and  will,"  and  in  that  case,  as  he  undertakes  to  prove, 
it  is  an  "  efficient  cause." 

The  rejection  of  "  final  causes,"  Bacon's  "  barren 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  103 

virgins,"  is  inevitable.  It  is  indeed  obvious  that  the 
conception  is  altogether  out  of  place  from  Hobbes's 
point  of  view;  that  is,  from  a  thoroughgoing 
mechanical  explanation  of  the  universe.  What  we 
have  to  do  is  to  trace  the  series  of  movements  of  the 
whole  set  of  interacting  bodies.  At  every  stage  the 
motion  of  each  body  is  the  resultant  of  its  own  pre- 
vious movement  and  of  the  movement  of  the  various 
bodies  which  have  come  into  contact  with  it.  Why 
does  a  projectile  move  in  a  certain  direction  and  with 
a  certain  velocity  ?  The  answer  is  given  by  its  pre- 
vious state,  and  the  explosive  or  restraining  forces 
which  have  modified  that  state.  Each  of  these  forces 
means  that  other  bodies  have  come  into  contact  with 
it  and  modified  its  conduct  in  accordance  with  the 
laws  of  motion.  So  far,  obviously,  we  have  nothing 
to  do  with  "  end r>  in  the  sense  of  purpose.  We  are 
tracing  a  single  process  backwards  and  forwards.  If, 
again,  we  take  a  mechanism,  such  as  the  clock,  which 
plays  so  conspicuous  a  part  in  the  illustration  of  "  final 
causes,"  we  explain  the  movement  of  the  hands  by 
the  various  wheels,  chains,  and  so  forth  which  trans- 
mit motion  from  the  weight  or  spring.  If  we  trace 
the  process  backward,  we  come  to  the  point  at  which 
the  clock  itself  was  put  together.  The  cause  then 
is  the  set  of  processes,  including  on  the  one  hand  the 
muscular  movements  of  the  clockmaker,  and  on  the 
other,  the  movements  impressed  upon  the  materials. 
All  that  man  does  is  to  move  one  bit  of  matter  to  or 
from  another.  The  clockmaker's  actions,  again,  are 
determined  by  his  purpose,  by  his  "end,"  and  the 
means  which  his  calculations  prescribe  for  securing  the 
end.  But  now,  according  to  Hobbes,  the  clockmaker 


104  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

is  just  as  much  an  automaton  as  the  clock.  His  per- 
ceptions, calculations,  and  motives  are  movements  in 
his  brain,  due  to  the  impact  of  external  bodies  upon 
the  organs  of  sense  and  the  reaction  which  takes  place 
in  the  brain.  They  are  the  "  efficient  cause  "  of  the 
clock,  and  the  so-called  "  final  cause  "  is  merely  a  name 
for  the  same  set  of  processes  absolutely  determined  by 
the  preceding  processes.  The  man  desires  and  expects, 
but  the  senses  and  expectations  are  themselves  part  of 
the  movements  implied.  It  is  clear  that  from  Hobbes's 
point  of  view,  the  so-called  "  final  cause  7  is  a  mere 
name  for  the  efficient  cause,  considered  in  one  relation, 
and  that  the  whole  series  of  events  is  purely  mechanical. 
Hobbes,  it  is  true,  professes  to  believe  in  a  Creator 
who  once  put  the  world  together  and  must  have 
intended  whatever  comes  to  pass ;  but  science  can  only 
trace  the  series  of  events  and  ask  what  was  the  pre- 
ceding state  from  which  any  given  state  is  generated. 
The  fact  that  everything  was  intended  does  not  ex- 
plain how  everything  comes  to  pass  ;  and  to  diverge 
from  the  question  how  things  actually  happen  to  the 
question  why  they  should  happen,  is  to  leave  the 
ground  of  science  and  to  get  merely  nugatory  answers, 
diverting  us  from  the  right  line  of  real  investigation. 

One  other  point  is  characteristic  of  Hobbes's  system. 
Whatever  happens,  he  holds,  happens  necessarily. 
Moreover,  whatever  does  not  happen  is  impossible. 
"  Every  act  which  is  not  impossible,"  as  he  puts  it, 
"  shall  at  some  time  be  produced."  There  is  no 
such  thing  as  contingency.  "  That  is  called  contin- 
gent," he  says,  "  of  which  the  necessary  cause  is  not  yet 
perceived."  That  is  to  say,  it  is  not  only  "  necessary  ' 
that,  if  the  solar  system  was  put  together  in  a  certain 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  105 

way,  certain  results  should  follow,  or  that  if  a  sparrow 
is  shot,  he  should  fall  to  the  ground;  but  it  is  also 
necessary  that  the  solar  system  should  be  just  what  it 
is,  and  that  the  sparrow  and  the  shot  should  have 
come  into  collision  just  when  they  actually  did. 

Omitting  certain  deviations  into  mathematical  specu- 
lation and  circle-squaring,  we  come  in  the  last  part  of 
the  De  Corpore  to  an  important  step  towards  the 
solution  of  a  difficulty  already  indicated.  We  have 
now  to  consider  "  Physics  or  the  phenomena  of  nature." 
He  gives  theories  of  light,  the  tides,  and  gravitation, 
and  it  is  needless  to  say  that  upon  such  matters  it 
was  impossible  for  him  to  reach  any  valuable  results. 
His  view  of  the  proper  method  of  treatment,  however, 
implies  an  important  doctrine.  "  Philosophy,"  as  we 
have  seen,  may  either  deduce  effects  from  causes  or 
causes  from  effects.  Hitherto  he  has  confined  himself 
to  the  first  —  the  deduction  of  effects  from  causes.  He 
has  been  able  to  start  from  definitions  —  from  the 
truths  which  we  "  create  ourselves  r  —  and  he  has,  as 
he  maintains,  affirmed  nothing  except  the  definitions 
themselves,  or  the  propositions  which  can  be  logically 
inferred  therefrom:  that  is  to  say,  "nothing  which 
is  not  sufficiently  demonstrated  to  all  those  that  agree 
with  me  in  the  use  of  words  and  appellations ;  for  whose 
sake  only  I  have  written  the  same."  But  now  we 
have  to  change  the  method.  We  start  from  "  the 
appearances  of  nature,"  which  are  known  to  us  by 
sense.  Our  first  principles  are  not  such  as  are  im- 
pressed by  definitions,  "  but  such  as  being  placed  in 
the  things  themselves  by  the  author  of  nature,  are  by 
us  observed  in  them  ;  and  we  make  use  of  them  in 
simple  and  particular,  not  universal  propositions." 


106  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

The  senses,  as  we  have  already  seen,  give  only  empirical 
knowledge,  which  is  made  up  of  merely  probable 
statements,  such  as  "  clouds  are  a  sign  of  rain,"  and 
cannot  reveal  those  necessary  truths  of  which  alone 
science  consists.  This  would  be  the  point  at  which 
we  might  expect  something  about  the  Baconian 
methods  of  induction.  Hobbes  takes  a  different  line. 
We  are  to  reason  about  phenomena  :  and  "  of  all 
phenomena  or  appearances  which  are  near  us,  the 
most  admirable  is  apparition  itself,  TO  <jf>cuVeo-0ai : 
namely,  that  some  natural  bodies  have  in  themselves 
the  patterns  almost  of  all  things,  and  others  of  none 
at  all."  By  the  patterns  (exemplaria)  he  means  the 
"  phantasms  "  which  exist  only  in  the  thinking  bodies  — 
in  men,  not  in  stones.  What  then  is  the  cause  of  these 
"ideas  and  phantasms  which  are  perpetually  generated 
within  us "  ?  Since  they  are  continually  changing, 
they  must  be  due  to  some  change  "in  the  sentient." 
Since  all  change  is  motion,  again,  this  implies  that  the 
senses  are  due  to  motion  in  the  organs  of  sense.  The 
object  is  some  "remote  body,"  from  which  pressure  is 
propagated  to  the  organ,  and  the  consequent  endeavour 
or  reaction  of  the  organ.  "  Endeavour  "  he  has  defined 
in  a  previous  passage  to  be  "motion  made  in  less  time 
and  space  than  can  be  given ;  or  motion  through  the 
length  of  a  point,  and  in  an  instant  or  point  of  time." 
Sense,  then,  is  the  phantasm  made  by  the  "  endeavour  ' 
outward  in  the  organ,  which  is  reaction  against  the 
endeavour  inwards  from  the  object.  Something  very 
like  this  may  be  read  in  modern  books,  which  tell  us 
how  the  stimulus  to  the  nerve  transmits  molecular 
movement  to  the  brain,  and  sets  up  a  reflex  action. 
Hobbes,  however,  could  only  speak  very  vaguely,  and 


ii.]  THE   WORLD  107 

takes  for  granted  much  now  exploded  physiology.  He 
is  a  little  doubtful  about  one  point.  Some  philosophers 
have  maintained  that  "all  bodies  are  endued  with  sense." 
If  sense  were  made  by  reaction  alone,  their  argument 
would  be  unanswerable.  It  is,  however,  the  possession 
of  organs  by  living  bodies  which  makes  the  difference. 
The  organs  preserve  the  motions  set  up  in  them : 
whereas  in  inanimate  bodies  the  motion  or  reaction 
must  cease  as  soon  as  the  external  pressure  ceases, 
and  the  phantasm  which  it  causes  vanishes  instantane- 
ously. Sense,  to  be  of  any  use  in  giving  knowledge, 
must  be  accompanied  with  memory,  for  the  knowledge 
which  it  gives  depends  upon  the  comparison  of  the 
phantasms.  This  suggests  one  of  his  significant 
phrases.  "  It  is  almost  all  one  for  a  man  to  be  always 
sensible  of  one  and  the  same  thing,  and  not  to  be 
sensible  at  all  of  any  things,"  or,  in  his  pithier  Latin, 
"  sentire  semper  idem  et  non  sent  ire  ad  idem  recidunt" 
Imagination,  again,  is  "  nothing  else  but  sense  decay- 
ing or  weakened  by  the  absence  of  object."  The  dif- 
ficulty remains,  how  memory,  which  is  thus  necessary 
for  the  comparison  of  phantasms  and  all  knowledge 
derived  from  the  senses,  can  be  interpreted  in  terms 
of  motion.  It  seems  as  if  we  still  required  a  mind 
different  from  the  organ  to  look  on  and  compare  the 
decaying  senses.  Self-consciousness  remains  a  mystery. 
Hobbes  answers  Descartes's  "Je  pense"  by  saying 
that  we  cannot  have  a  thought  of  a  thought;  but  he 
holds  that  memory  is  a  feeling  of  a  feeling.  Sentire  se 
sentisse,  meminisse  est. 

This  involves  another  remark.     Hobbes  insists  em- 
phatically that  the  phantasm  is  somehow  quite  different  • 
from  the  motion  by  which  it  is  caused.    He  had  already 


108  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

pointed  out  in  the  Human  Nature  that  people  easily 
fancy  that  colour  and  shape  belong  to  the  object,  or 
that  the  sound  is  in  the  bell.  The  opinion  has  been 
so  long  received  that  the  contrary  must  seem  a  para- 
dox. Yet  the  common  view  involves  the  introduction 
of  the  old  "  species  visible  and  intelligible  "  :  it  is  "  worse 
than  a  paradox  —  an  impossibility."  The  colour  and 
"  image  "  are  "  nothing  without  us."  They  are  appari- 
tions due  to  the  motions  in  the  brain.1  The  senses  are 
deceptive,  as  when  men  "divers  times'1  see  objects 
double,  or  take  a  reflected  image  for  a  reality,  or  see 
a  flash  of  light  from  a  blow  on  the  eye.  The  same  is 
true  of  the  other  senses.  Smells  and  tastes  vary  from 
man  to  man.  The  heat  which  we  feel  from  the  fire  is 
manifestly  in  us  and  not  in  the  fire,  for  it  gives  pleasure 
and  pain,  "  whereas  in  the  coal  there  is  no  such  thing." 
The  "paradox"  is  now  a  familiar  truth.  Hobbes 
seems  to  go  beyond^ his  immediate  successors.  They 
would  admit  that  the  so-called  "  secondary  qualities," 
colour,  and  so  forth,  are  purely  subjective;  but  the 
primary  qualities,  space  and  solidity,  seemed  to  have 
superior  claim  to  "  objective  reality."  Hobbes  observes 
that  place  and  time,  that  is  to  say,  magnitude  and 
duration,  "  are  only  our  own  fancies  of  a  body  simply 
so  called ;  "  that  is,  of  a  body  considered  without  refer- 
ence to  its  other  properties. 

All  our  knowledge  of  phenomena  depends  upon  the 
senses,  and  what  the  senses  present  to  us  are  simply 
the  unreal  phantasms,  upon  which,  it  would  seem,  no 

1In  a  dedicatory  letter  of  an  imprinted  treatise  upon  optics, 
he  says  that  he  had  stated  this  theory  to  Newcastle  about 
1630;  and  appeals  to  him  as  a  witness:  the  same  doctrine 
having  heen  since  published  by  another. 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  109 

real  science  or  body  of  demonstrable  truths  can  be 
erected.  The  cause  of  the  phantasms,  again,  is  the 
"endeavour"  of  the  organ  —  infinitesimal  movements 
which  take  place  within  the  length  of  a  point.  Hobbes 
here  denies  emphatically  that  "  infinite  "  has  any  real 
meaning  beyond  "  indefinite,"  whether  indefinitely 
great  or  small.  Men  who  profess  to  reason  about  the 
infinite  and  eternal  are  "  not  idiots,  but,  which  makes 
the  absurdity  unpardonable,  geometricians,  and  such 
as  take  upon  them  to  be  judges."  They  get  entangled 
in  words  to  which  there  is  no  corresponding  idea,  and 
"are  forced  either  to  speak  something  absurd,  or, 
which  they  love  worse,  to  hold  their  peace."  No 
limits,  however,  may  be  assigned  to  possible  greatness 
or  smallness.  Microscopes  now  show  things  a  hundred 
thousand  times  bigger  than  they  appear  to  bare  eyes, 
and  might  be  made  so  as  to  magnify  each  part  a 
hundred  thousand  times  more.  So  we  now  know  that 
the  distance  from  the  earth  to  the  sun  is  but  as  a  point 
in  comparison  with  the  distance  from  the  sun  to  the 
fixed  stars.  Hobbes  was  impressed  by  these  recent 
revelations  of  the  enormous  vistas  opened  by  early 
science,  which  have  become  still  more  impressive  as 
science  has  grown.  They  suggested  to  him  the  im- 
possibility of  building  up  scientific  knowledge  011  the 
direct  basis  of  observation.  Everything  depends  upon 
motion ;  but  the  motions  which  are  causes  of  the  phan- 
tasms or  of  natural  phenomena  are  too  infinitesimal 
to  be  perceived.  Their  existence  may  be  inferred,  but 
their  precise  nature  can  only  be  guessed.  When, 
therefore,  we  proceed  from  the  phenomena  given  by 
sense  to  the  causes,  we  can  no  longer  start  from  the 
definitions  which,  in  the  previous  inquiry,  state  our 


110  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

first  principles.  We  have  instead  of  that  method  to 
start  from  hypotheses.  Hobbes  aims  at  showing  some 
"  ways  and  means  by  which  they  (appearances)  may 
be,  I  do  not  say  they  are,  generated."  He  ends  his 
discussion  of  the  phenomena  by  declaring  that  the 
hypotheses  which  he  has  assumed  are  "  both  possible 
and  easy  to  be  comprehended,"  and  that  he  has  reasoned 
rightly  from  them.  "  If  any  other  man  will  demonstrate 
the  same  and  greater  things  from  other  hypotheses, 
there  will  be  greater  praise  and  thanks  due  to  him 
than  I  demand  for  myself,  provided  his  hypotheses 
are  conceivable."  At  any  rate  he  has  got  rid  of 
empty  words,  such  as  "  substantial  forms,"  "  incorpo- 
real substances,"  "  antipathy,"  "  sympathy,"  and 
"  occult  quality." 

So  far  it  seems  that  Hobbes's  method  was  that  of 
modern  sciences.  Their  aim,  like  his,  is  to  give  a 
mathematical  theory  of  the  various  natural  forces, 
such  as  heat,  light,  and  electricity.  They  begin  by  a 
hypothesis  about  atoms  and  molecules  which  must  be 
conceivable,  and  represent  such  properties  of  matter 
as  we  know  to  exist,  although  no  direct  observations 
can  reveal  them.  If,  again,  these  assumptions  enable 
us  to  formulate  the  observed  "  laws,"  and  to  predict 
what  will  happen  in  other  cases,  and  if  no  other 
assumptions  can  satisfy  the  conditions,  we  regard  the 
successful  assumptions  as  proved,  or  at  least  as  pro- 
visionally established,  though,  it  may  be,  in  need  of 
modification  or  of  some  further  assumptions  which 
may  make  them  more  complete.  The  difference  is 
that  the  vast  improvement  both  in  instruments  of 
observation  and  in  methods  of  mathematical  calcula- 
tion enable  us  to  apply  incomparably  more  searching 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  111 

tests  to  our  hypotheses,  as  well  as  to  gain  confidence 
from  the  reciprocal  support  given  to  each  other  by 
different  departments  of  investigation.  Hobbes  had 
to  be  vague  and  audacious,  and  make  erroneous  physi- 
cal assumptions.  He  was  still  in  the  period  of  Des- 
cartes's  vortices,  and  could  not  anticipate  Newton's 
theory  of  gravitation. 

His  physical  speculations  have  therefore  no  interest, 
except  as  specimens  of  the  early  guessing  with  which 
men  had  to  be  content  at  the  dawn  of  science.  The 
general  conception  of  the  possibility  of  working  out 
mathematical  theories  of  physical  sciences  shows  that 
he  was  fully  awake  to  the  most  important  movement 
of  thought  in  his  own  day,  and  ready,  in  spite  of  his 
odd  misconceptions,  to  adopt  the  results  of  the  great 
teachers,  such  as  Galileo  and  Harvey.  But  we  have 
now  to  look  at  another  point.  The  "  motions r  or 
"  endeavours "  in  the  bodily  organs  which  generate 
the  phantasms  of  the  senses,  generate  also,  as  he 
remarks,  "  another  kind  of  sense  .  .  .  namely,  the 
sense  of  pleasure  and  pain,"  which  he  fancies  to  pro- 
ceed from,  the  action  of  the  heart.  This  doctrine  he 
takes  to  be  favoured  by  Harvey's  discovery.  It  is 
clear,  however,  that  here  we  come  to  a  difficulty. 
What  we  know  directly  are  the  phantasms  :  the  sensa- 
tions of  light,  heat,  and  so  forth,  or  the  pleasures  and 
pains  which  are  indissolubly  connected  with  certain 
sense-given  phenomena.  Now  if  we  could  discover 
what  are  the  motions  which  take  place  when  we  see 
or  hear  or  feel  pain  or  pleasure,  there  is  still  a  gap, 
corresponding  to  his  remark  about  the  TO  <f>a.iveo-0ai. 
Why  a  sensation  of  light  should  follow  a  motion  in 
the  optic  nerve,  or  pain  or  pleasure  be  connected  with 


112  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

certain  changes  in  the  organism,  remains  a  mystery. 
That,  in  fact,  is  the  difficulty  which  has  been  awaiting 
him  all  along.  When  he  comes  to  his  theory  of  human 
nature,  he  still  tries  to  connect  his  doctrine  with  his 
general  theory  of  motion  in  the  nerves,  but  is  forced 
to  rely  to  some  extent  upon  empirical  psychology.  He 
knows  how  men  will  act  in  given  circumstances,  not 
because  he  can  deduce  the  action  from  any  theory 
about  the  bodily  organism,  but  because  he  observes 
that,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  such  and  such  things  are 
painful  or  pleasurable  and  lead  to  aversion  or  desire. 
He  puts  the  case  himself  in  a  remarkable  passage. 
The  natural  philosopher,  as  we  have  seen,  must  begin 
from  geometry;  "  civil  and  moral  philosophy"  properly 
depend  upon  natural.  But,  he  says,  "  the  causes  of 
the  motions  of  the  mind  are  known,  not  only  by  ratio- 
cination, but  also  by  the  experience  of  every  man  that 
takes  the  pains  to  observe  those  motions  within  him- 
self." Therefore  we  may  either  take  the  "  synthetical 
method,"  and  from  "  the  very  first  principles  of  philo- 
sophy "  deduce  "  the  causes  and  necessity  of  "creating 
commonwealths  "  ;  or,  even  without  knowing  geometry 
and  physics,  we  may  attain  the  principles  of  civil 
philosophy  by  the  "  analytical ';  method.  The  syn- 
thetical method  proceeds  from  "  motions  of  the  mind  "  ; 
the  knowledge  of  these  motions,  again,  follows  from 
knowledge  of  "  sense  or  imagination,"  and  ultimately 
depends  upon  geometry.  But  the  analytical  method 
starts  from  a  knowledge  of  law  as  dependent  upon 
"  power  "  :  of  power  as  derived  from  the  wills  of  the 
men  "  that  constitute  such  power,"  and  that  again 
from  a  knowledge  of  men's  appetites  and  passions. 
That  knowledge  is  to  be  derived  from  every  man's 


ii.]  THE    WORLD  113 

experience  if  lie  will  but  "examine  his  own  mind." 
That  is  fortunate.  If  we  had  to  deduce  the  nature  of 
government  and  of  right  and  wrong  from  geometry 
or  physics,  we  should  have  to  wait  a  long  time 
for  a.ny  satisfactory  results.  The  materialist  theory 
remains  in  Hobbes's  mind  as  a  self-evident  truth, 
and  has  a  very  important  influence  upon  his  specula- 
tions. But  his  real  method  is  different.  That  will 
appear  hereafter. 


CHAPTER  III 

MAN1 

1.  Psychology 

MAN  is  a  body  with  certain  organs.  Other  bodies 
coming  into  contact  with  the  organs  of  sense  pro- 
pagate motions  through  the  nerves  to  the  brain  and 
heart.  The  reactions  or  "  endeavours  "  set  up  in  the 
central  organs  generate  the  sensations  or  phantasms 
which  constitute  the  whole  mental  world.  We  are 
directly  conscious  of  nothing  else,  although  they 
enable  us  to  perceive  what  happens  "outside  of  the 
mind."  The  laws  of  motion,  again,  tell  us  that  a  thing 
once  in  motion  "  will  be  eternally  in  motion  unless 
somewhat  else  stay  it."  Whatever  hindereth  it  will 

1  The  second  part  of  Hobbes's  philosophy  considered  in  this 
chapter  is  expounded  in  the  early  chapters  of  the  Leviathan 
(vol.  iii.  of  English  works)  and  the  Human  Nature.  The  last, 
originally  published  in  1650,  consists  of  the  first  thirteen 
chapters  of  the  treatise  written  in  1640.  The  later  part  of  the 
same  treatise  also  appeared  in  1650  as  De  Corpore  Politico. 
These  two  form  the  fourth  volume  of  the  English  works.  A 
later  treatise,  De  Ho  mine,  in  Latin,  appeared  in  1658,  but  adds 
nothing  to  the  earlier  books.  Hobbes  never  found  himself 
able  to  give  the  fuller  exposition  which  he  had  intended  of 
the  doctrines  summarised  in  the  Human  Nature  and  the 
Leviathan;  but  he  states  the  essence  with  sufficient  terseness 
and  clearness. 

114 


CHAP,  in.]  MAN  115 

take  some  time  to  destroy  the  motion.  "  Though  the 
wind  cease,  the  waves  give  not  over  rolling  for  a  long 
time  after ;  so  also  it  happeneth  in  that  motion  which 
is  made  in  the  internal  parts  of  a  man,  then,  when  he 
sees,  dreams,  etc."  The  "  image  "  thus  formed  remains 
for  a  time  after  the  object  is  removed,  and  the  faculty 
of  retaining  such  images  is  therefore  called  "  the 
imagination."  Imagination  is  therefore  "  nothing 
but  decaying  sense."  All  knowledge  and  thought 
thus  correspond  to  the  action  and  reaction  between 
the  living  body  and  the  bodies  which  impinge  upon 
it.  Knowledge,  therefore,  is  entirely  constructed  from 
experience,  or  from  the  action  set  up  from  outside, 
although  the  organised  body  has  the  power  of  reacting 
and  so  generating  the  phantasms  which  compose  the 
"imaginary"  or  mental  world.  The  problem  which 
Hobbes  now  considers  is  how  the  mind  or  brain  coines 
to  systematise  this  varying  play  of  imagery  and  to 
acquire  both  general  truths  and  rules  which  govern 
conduct.  We  have  already  seen  what  is  the  logic 
which  is  worked  out  by  the  help  of  language ;  but  we 
have  also  to  consider  man  as  an  acting  and  feeling 
being.  We  must  understand  not  only  his  methods  of 
reasoning  but  the  motives  which  govern  his  conduct. 
Although  Hobbes  holds  that  the  phantasms  are 
caused  by  the  internal  motions,  this  cause  does  not 
really  help  us  much  to  explain  the  effect.  We  have  to 
look  at  the  phantasms  themselves.  Hobbes  is  naturally 
much  interested  by  the  phenomena  of  dreaming,  for 
dreams  are  entirely  made  up  of  phantasms.  We  catch 
the  phantasms,  so  to  speak,  by  themselves,  shifting,  com- 
bining, and  behaving  according  to  their  own  purpose. 
Sleep  is  a  "  privation  of  the  act  of  sense."  The  power 


116  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

to  feel  remains,  but  its  activity  is  suspended  for  the 
time.  Consequently  the  phantasms  are  not  suppressed 
or  modified  by  the  intrusion  of  images  from  without. 
They  are  made  up  entirely  of  past  images,  though 
combined  in  new  and  apparently  arbitrary  ways. 
Sometimes  they  continue  the  train  of  images  of  the 
waking  state,  but  they  also  seem  to  spring  up  of 
themselves.  The  explanation  is  that  there  is  a 
reciprocal  action  between  the  vital  organs  and  the 
phantasms.  "  Sad  imaginations  nourish  the  spleen, 
and  a  strong  spleen  reciprocally  causeth  fearful 
dreams."  When  we  are  awake  fear  causes  cold,  and 
when  we  are  asleep  cold  causes  fear,  and  therefore 
"  dreams  of  ghosts."  This  leads  to  an  important 
result  which  will  meet  us  again.  Fear,  "  helped  a 
little  with  stories  of  such  apparitions,  causes  guilty 
men  in  the  night  and  in  hallowed  places  to  see  terrible 
phantasms  which  they  mistake  for  real  ghosts  and 
incorporeal  substances."  Our  dreams  are  thus  the 
reverse  of  our  waking  imaginations :  the  motion  when 
we  are  awake  beginning  at  one  end,  and  when  we 
dream  at  the  other.  The  absence  of  interfering  sen- 
sations, again,  makes  the  phantasms  as  clear  as  the 
waking  impressions,  and  as  they  appear  to  be  always 
present  and  we  do  not  remember  or  reflect,  strange 
things  in  dreams  cause  no  wonder.  Finally,  the  inco- 
herence of  our  dreams  distinguishes  them  sufficiently 
from  the  phantasms  which,  when  we  are  awake,  inform 
us  of  a  present  reality.  When  dreaming  we  do  not 
know  that  we  are  not  awake,  but  when  we  are  awake 
we  are  quite  sure  that  we  are  not  dreaming.  "  We  do 
not  dream  of  the  absurdities  of  our  waking  thoughts," 
but  when  awake  we  perceive  the  incoherence  of  our 


in.]  MAN  117 

dreams.  In  dreams  "our  thoughts  appear  like  the 
stars  between  flying  clouds,  not  in  the  order  in  which 
a  man  would  choose  to  observe  them,  but  as  the 
uncertain  order  of  flying  clouds  permits." 

What  is  it,  then,  that  gives  this  colouring  to  our 
waking  thoughts  ?  "  Not  every  thought  to  every 
thought  succeeds  indifferently."  Our  images  are 
relics  of  past  sense  impressions,  and,  moreover,  they 
succeed  in  the  same  order  in  which  their  originals 
succeeded.  One  follows  the  other  "  as  water  upon 
a  plane  table  is  drawn  which  way  any  one  part  is 
guided  by  the  finger."  But  we  have  experience  of 
images  succeeding  in  the  most  various  orders.  There 
is,  therefore,  no  certainty  as  to  what  image  will  succeed 
another  at  a  given  time,  although  it  is  certain  that 
the  order  is  one  in  which  we  have  previously  experi- 
enced them.  Thus  thoughts  seem  "impertinent  to 
one  another  "  as  in  a  dream.  Yet  even  in  this  "  wild 
ranging  of  the  mind '  we  may  often  perceive  the 
guiding  cause.  "For  in  a  discourse  of  our  present 
civil  war  what  could  seem  more  impertinent  than  to 
ask,  as  one  did,  what  is  the  value  of  a  Eoman  pcni,y. 
Yet  the  coherence  to  me  was  manifest  enough.  For 
the  thought  of  the  war  introduced  the  thought  of  the 
delivering  up  of  the  king  to  his  enemies ;  the  thought 
of  that  thought  brought  in  the  thought  of  the  deliver- 
ing up  of  Christ ;  and  that  again  the  thought  of  the 
thirty  pence,  which  was  the  price  of  that  treason ;  and 
thence  easily  followed  that  malicious  question,  and  all 
this  in  a  moment  of  time,  for  thought  is  quick."  This 
passage,  quoted  by  all  critics  of  Hobbes,  is  a  fine  speci- 
men of  his  pregnant  style.  G.  H.  Lewes  remarks  that 
a  popular  rhetorician  would  have  expanded  the  last 


118  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

four  words  into  a  paragraph.  A  Scottish  professor 
would  have  proceeded  to  quote  Akenside.  It  is  also 
remarkable  as  an  illustration  of  the  doctrine  of  the 
"  association  of  ideas "  which  was  to  become  so  pro- 
minent with  Hobbes's  successors.  It  has  been  pointed 
out,  indeed,  that  Hobbes  was  not  the  first  person  to 
notice  a  phenomenon  which  had  already  been  observed 
by  Aristotle.  ISTor  has  it  with  him  the  importance 
which  it  assumed  in  later  years.  Hume  declared 
that  the  association  of  ideas  was  in  mental  phenomena 
what  gravitation  was  in  astronomy,  and  Hartley's  later 
application  of  the  doctrine  to  the  moral  as  well  as 
the  intellectual  nature,  became  the  guiding  principle 
of  the  later  empirical  school  in  England.  Hartley's 
"  vibrati uncles ':  play  the  same  part  as  Hobbes's 
"  endeavours,"  and  in  both  cases  the  physiological 
theory,  which  professes  to  give  the  ground  of  the 
phenomena,  is  rather  deduced  from  the  phenomena 
themselves  than  independently  ascertained.  The 
"  association  of  ideas ':  remained  when  the  vibrati- 
uncles  were  dropped.  To  Hartley's  followers  it 
scenic  ,1  that  the  whole  theory  of  knowledge  depended 
upon  a  thorough  carrying  out  of  this  principle.  Logic 
in  general  seemed  to  them  to  be  derivable  from  "asso- 
ciation of  ideas."  Though  Hobbes  certainly  did  not 
foresee  this  application  of  his  statement,  his  use  of  the 
observation  is  important.  The  "  trains  of  thoughts," 
as  he  says,  are  of  two  kinds :  the  first  is  "unguided"  ; 
when  thoughts  are  directed  by  association,  and  the 
succession  appears  to  be  as  casual  as  in  a  dream :  the 
second  is  "  regulated  by  some  desire  or  design."  The 
unregulated  give  us  the  kind  of  knowledge  which 
would  be  described  by  Hume  as  attributable  to  the 


in.]  MAN  110 

association  of  ideas.  We  remember  things  as  ante- 
cedent and  consequent,  and  this  remembrance  is  an 
"  experiment,"  whether  made  voluntarily,  as  when  we 
put  a  thing  in  the  fire  to  see  what  will  happen,  or 
"  not  made,"  as  when  we  remember  a  fair  morning 
after  a  cold  evening.  When  we  have  often  observed 
such  a  sequence  we  expect  its  repetition,  and  from 
this  comes  the  kind  of  knowledge  which  we  call 
"  prudence."  If  the  sign  has  preceded  the  event  in  a 
required  number  of  cases,  it  may  justify  us  in  betting 
twenty  to  one  that  an  event  will  happen,  but  never 
justifies  a  certainty,  which  belongs  to  science  alone. 

At  this  stage,  then,  cause  and  effect  are  represented 
simply  by  sequence  —  the  sole  meaning,  according  to 
the  later  empiricists,  of  cause  and  effect.  Now  when  a 
man  desires  some  end,  he  thinks  of  the  means  which 
will  produce  it.  This  kind  of  thinking  Hobbes  takes 
to  be  common  to  man  and  beast,  though  it  is  man 
alone  who  is  capable  of  following  the  reverse  method 
of  deducing  effects  from  causes.  That  method  is 
peculiar  to  truly  scientific  reasoning.  The  "  discourse 
of  the  mind,"  when  directed  by  design,  may  lead  to 
either  process.  A  man  has  lost  something,  and  his 
mind  runs  back  from  place  to  place  and  time  to  time 
to  find  when  and  where  he  had  it,  for  he  knows  the 
place  in  which  he  is  to  seek,  and  "  his  thoughts  run 
over  all  the  parts  thereof  in  the  same  manner  as  one 
would  sweep  a  room  to  find  a  jewel,  or  as  a  spaniel 
ranges  a  field  till  he  find  a  scent,  or  as  a  man  should  run 
over  the  alphabet  to  start  a  rhyme."  In  other  cases  a 
man  comes  to  know  what  event  will  follow  an  action. 
He  wishes  to  know,  for  example,  what  will  be  the 
consequence  of  committing  a  crime.  He  assumes  that 


120  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

like  events  will  follow  like  actions  and  so  he  thinks 
of  the  sequence  of  "the  crime,  the  officer,  the  prison, 
the  judge,  and  the  gallows."  That  is  a  course  of  reflec- 
tion which,  as  Hobbes  undeniably  says,  is  likely  to 
result  in  "prudence."  Here  again  Hobbes  emphasises 
a  distinction  between  "  prudence  "  and  "  science,"  or 
between  merely  empirical  and  necessary  truth.  He 
therefore  introduces  at  this  point  his  theory  of  names 
and  "  computation  "  —  the  method  by  which  science  is 
elaborated.  But  when  he  is  taking  the  psychological 
rather  than  the  logical  view,  and  considering  how  as  a 
matter  of  fact  knowledge  is  developed,  he  makes  the 
distinction  less  absolute.  Science  "  after  all '  is  a 
development  of  "prudence."1  Both  kinds  of  know- 
ledge, he  says  in  the  Human  Nature,  "  are  but  experi- 
ence," though  science  depends  upon  the  "  proper  use  of 
names  in  language."  This,  however,  implies  the  "  con- 
comitance of  conception  with  words :  for  if  words 
alone  were  sufficient,  a  parrot  might  be  taught  as  well 
to  know  truth  as  to  speak  it.  Evidence  is  to  truth,  as 
the  sap  to  the  tree,  which  so  far  as  it  creepeth  along 
with  the  body  and  branches  keepeth  them  alive ;  where 
it  forsaketh  them,  they  die ;  for  this  evidence,  which 
is  meaning  with  our  words,  is  the  life  of  truth."  So 
in  the  Leviathan  he  remarks  that  children  before  they 
can  speak  are  not  properly  reasonable,  and  most  men 
are  little  better.  Having  no  science  or  knowledge  of 
consequences,  they  still  resemble  children,  who  are 
made  to  believe  that  their  new  brothers  and  sisters 
are  found  in  the  garden.  Such  natural  "prudence," 
indeed,  is  better  than  false  rules.  "The  light  of 

1  See    chapter    vi.    of    Human    Nature,    and    chapter   v.    of 
Leviathan. 


in.]  MAN  121 

human  reason  is  perspicuous  words,  but  by  exact 
definitions  first  snuffed  and  purged  from  ambiguity. 
Reason  is  the  pace;  increase  of  science  the  way;  and 
the  benefit  of  mankind  the  end."  The  ability  of  the 
man  who  has  natural  dexterity  with  his  weapon  is  to 
the  ability  of  the  man  who  has  thoroughly  acquired  the 
art  of  fencing,  as  prudence  to  "sapience"  (sapientia, 
that  is,  or  science).  "Both  (abilities)  are  useful;  but 
the  latter  infallible."  Those,  meanwhile,  who  trust  to 
books  and  follow  the  blind  blindly  are  "like  him  that, 
trusting  to  the  false,  rules  of  a  master  of  fence, 
ventures  presumptuously  upon  an  adversary  that 
either  kills  or  disgraces  him."  Thus  in  any  business 
where  we  have  no  "  infallible  science,"  it  is  better  to 
follow  our  "natural  judgment  than  to  be  guided  by 
general  sentences  read  in  authors."  Politicians  love 
to  show  their  reading  in  councils,  but  very  few  do  it 
in  their  domestic  affairs:  having  prudence  enough  at 
home,  though  in  "  public  they  study  more  the  reputa- 
tion of  their  own  wit  than  the  success  of  another's 
business."  The  accurate  knowledge  which  comes  with 
a  "  proper  use  of  names  "  is  therefore,  as  it  would  seem, 
not  dependent  upon  "arbitrary  conventions'"  as  to 
names,  but  a  refinement  and  articulate  organisation  of 
the  simple  conceptions  out  of  which  mere  prudence  or 
a  system  of  empirical  knowledge  is  constructed. 

Another  point  has  now  to  be  considered.  Trains  of 
thought  are  "'regulated"  by  the  presence  of  some  aim 
or  desire.  The  wild  ranging  of  the  mind  represented 
by  dreams  or  mere  "  association  of  ideas ':  is  then 
directed  to  a  single  end.  We  have  noticed  sequences, 
such  as  the  crime,  the  prison,  the  gallows;  and  when  we 
desire,  we  think  of  the  means  which  will  produce  the 


122  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

desirable  result,  and  then  of  the  means  to  those  means. 
What  then  is  a  desire  ?  All  conceptions  and  appari- 
tions are  really  "  motion  in  some  internal  substance  of 
the  head."  The  motion  "  not  stopping  there  but  pro- 
ceeding to  the  heart,  of  necessity  must  there  either  help 
or  hinder  the  motion  which  is  called  vital:  when  it 
helpethit  is  called  delight,  contentment,  or  pleasure,  which 
is  nothing  really  but  motion  about  the  heart,  as  con- 
ception is  nothing  but  motion  in  the  head."  When,  on 
the  contrary,  the  vital  motion  is  hindered,  the  hindering 
motion  is  called  pain.  The  physiology  is  of  course 
absurd,  but  the  theory  thus  accepted  is  remarkable. 
The  same  doctrine  appears  in  Spinoza's  Ethics,  where 
it  becomes  the  foundation  of  his  famous  account  of 
the  passions,  held  by  many  critics  to  be  his  master- 
piece. Sir  F.  Pollock  in  his  admirable  exposition 
observes  that,  according  to  Spinoza,  "  Pleasure  marks 
the  rising  and  pain  the  lowering  of  the  vital  energies." 
That  phrase  would  serve  equally  as  an  equivalent 
for  the  words  just  quoted  from  Hobbes.  Sir  F. 
Pollock  points  out,  again,  that  this  doctrine  has 
been  accepted  by  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer  and  other 
modern  thinkers.  That  pleasure  and  pain  must  in 
some  way  correspond  to  heighten  or  lower  vitality  is 
a  doctrine  which  in  some  form  or  other  becomes  more 
essential  with  the  acceptance  of  evolution.  It  is  quite 
clear  that  while  animals,  human  or  other,  seek  for  the 
pleasurable  and  avoid  the  painful,  a  being  which  acted 
upon  the  opposite  plan  would  be  in  a  very  bad  way. 
A  race  which  hated  food  and  took  delight  in  being 
eaten  would  speedily  be  extinguished  in  the  struggle 
for  existence.  Spinoza  bases  his  theory  upon  his 
general  principle  —  everything  that  is  endeavours  to 


m.]  MAN  123 

persist  in  its  own  being  "  in  suo  esse  perseverare  co 
natur"  Hobbes's  acceptance  of  the  law  that  the 
motion  of  a  thing  will  persist  unless  altered  by  some 
other  thing,  implies  a  perception  of  the  same  principle. 
Meanwhile  he  insists  (in  the  Human  Nature)  upon 
another  point  of  great  importance. 

"  Ends,"  he  says,  may  be  near  at  hand  or  further  off : 
those  which  are  nearer  are  called  "  means "  to  the 
further.  "  But  for  an  utmost  end,  in  which  the 
ancient  philosophers  have  placed  felicity,  there  is  no 
such  thing  in  this  world,  nor  way  to  it,  more  than  to 
Utopia :  for  while  we  live  we  have  desires,  and  desire 
presupposeth  a  further  end."  There  can,  he  infers, 
"  be  no  contentment  but  in  proceeding."  We  are  not 
to  marvel,  therefore,  when  we  see  that  as  men  attain 
to  one  end,  "their  appetite  continually  groweth"  and 
they  pursue  some  other.  "  Of  those  that  have  attained 
to  the  highest  degree  of  honour  and  riches,  some  have 
affected  mastery  in  some  art ;  as  Nero  in  music  and 
poetry,  Commodus  in  the  art  of  a  gladiator ; '  some 
kind  of  diversion,  whether  in  play  or  business,  is  still 
required;  and  men  justly  complain  of  a  great  grief 
that  they  know  not  what  to  do.  "  Felicity,  therefore, 
by  which  we  mean  continual  delight,  consisteth  not  in 
having  prospered  but  in  prospering."  This  states  a 
really  valuable  doctrine.  Everything  we  have  seen  is 
motion:  knowledge  implies  perpetual  motion,  the 
whole  world-process  is  a  continuous  transformation  of 
one  system  of  motions  into  another ;  and  life,  of 
course,  is  essentially  motion.  To  wish,  therefore,  for 
"  Utopia,"  which  excludes  change,  is  to  wish  for  some- 
thing inconsistent  with  life  and  radically  inconceivable. 
Hobbes  constantly  ridicules  the  scholastic  doctrine  of 


124  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

eternity  as  a  "  nunc  stans,"  a  state  which  has  no  rela- 
tion to  time.  That  is  one  of  his  favourite  illustrations 
of  the  use  of  meaningless  words.  'The  universe  is 
change.  He  answers  by  anticipation  an  argument 
which  finds  favour  with  modern  pessimists.  Life,  they 
suggest,  is  essentially  misery,  because  we  are  always 
desiring,  and  desire  implies  want.  The  inference 
involves  a  fallacy.  Time  never  stands  still,  and  we  are 
always  moving  on.  We  cannot  sit  down  upon  a  solid 
lump  of  pleasure  outside  of  time  and  change.  We 
cannot  imagine  such  a  thing,  for  the  words  have  no 
real  meaning.  ((Every  end  is  also  a  beginning,  and  to 
think  of  the  future  is  to  desire.  But  desire  is  not 
necessarily  painful.  It  does  not  imply  dissatisfaction 
with  the  present,  but  only  a  hope  that  the  change 
may  lead  in  a  certain  direction.  If  the  conditions  of 
future  fruition  appear  to  be  present,  the  expectation 
of  change  is  itself  delightful.  We  have  in  Hobbes's 
language  appetites  and  aversions.  Appetite  is  an 
endeavour  towards  an  "  object  which  delighteth." 
"  Pleasure,  love,  and  appetite  are  divers  names  for 
divers  considerations  of  the  same  things."  Opposed 
to  "  appetite  "  is  "  aversion,"  which  "  moves  us  when 
the  object  displeaseth."  Happiness  implies,  therefore, 
such  a  process  as  involves  a  continuous  activity  of  the 
vital  powers  and  not  an  impossible  and  inconceivable 
state  of  changelessness.  We  cannot  arrest  time  or 
cease  the  change,  but  we  may  be  continually  moving 
along  the  line  of  greatest  vigour  and  happiness.  This 
again  seems  to  be  often  overlooked  by  Hobbes's 
disciples,  the  later  utilitarians.  Bentham  is  apt  to 
talk  about  "  lots"  of  happiness,  as  if  happiness  were  a 
solid  thing  capable  of  being  accumulated  like  coins  in 


in.]  MAN  125 

a  bag.  Life  is  a  continuous  process  in  which  pain  or 
pleasure  may  predominate,  but  its  value  is  to  be 
measured,  not  by  the  sum  of  things  possessed,  but  by 
the  nature  of  the  energy  evolved  in  possessing  them. 

This  leads  to  Hobbes's  theory  of  the  passions,  which, 
though  characteristic,  can  hardly  be  described,  like 
Spinoza's,  as  a  "masterpiece."  He  has  denned  passion 
as  "the  motion  about  the  heart,"  which  is  a  consequence 
of  "  the  motion  of  the  brain,"  which  we  call  conception. 
He  has  therefore  "  obliged  himself  to  search  out  and 
declare  from  what  conception  proceedeth  every  one  of 
the  passions  which  are  commonly  taken  notice  of." 
The  course  of  this  inquiry  is  curious.  He  begins  by 
a  brief  account  of  the  sensual  pains  and  pleasures. 
Among  them  are  the  pleasure  of  hearing.  Galileo 
has  done  something  towards  explaining  the  pleasures 
of  harmony;  but  "I  confess  that  I  know  not,"  says 
Hobbes,  "  for  what  reason  one  succession  in  tone  and 
measure  is  more  pleasant  than  another."  He  con- 
jectures that  some  airs  imitate  and  revive  a  former 
passion  •  "  for  no  air  pleaseth  but  for  a  time,  no  more 
doth  imitation."  There  is,  however,  "  another  delight 
by  the  ear,"  peculiar  to  musicians,  namely,  a  "  rejoicing 
of  their  own  skill."  Of  this  nature  he  says  "  are  the 
passions  of  which  I  am  to  speak  next."  He  is  really 
dropping  the  attempt  to  give  a  scientific  classification 
of  the  passions  in  order  to  dwell  upon  certain 
emotions  interesting  for  the  purpose  of  his  political 
theories. 

He  begins  from  a  sufficiently  wide  proposition. 
The  expectation  that  anything  will  happen  hereafter 
implies  the  knowledge  that  there  is  something  present 
which  has  power  to  produce  it;  that  knowledge  being 


126  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

derived  from  our  remembrance  of  the  past.  "  Where- 
fore all  conception  of  the  future  is  conception  of  power 
able  to  produce  something.  Whoever,  therefore,  ex- 
pecteth  pleasure  to  come  must  conceive  withal  some 
power  in  himself  by  which  the  same  may  be  attained.'7 
When  we  desire  a  pleasure,  we  no  doubt  conceive  our- 
selves to  have  the  power  of  enjoying  it.  We  may 
perhaps  desire  something,  while  recognising  that  under 
the  circumstances  it  is  impossible,  as  according  to  the 
poet,  the  moth  may  desire  the  star.  But  desire  as 
determining  action,  "the  beginning  of  animal  motion 
towards  something  that  pleaseth  us,"  supposes  that  we 
can  enjoy  and  that  we  can  act  so  as  to  procure  the 
enjoyment  or  the  chance  of  it.  This,  however,  does 
not  appear  to  throw  much  light  upon  the  nature  of 
desire  or  of  the  special  passions.  Hobbes  proceeds  to 
explain  that  by  "  power  "  he  means  all  the  faculties  of 
body  and  mind,  and,  besides  these,  all  such  further 
power  as  is  by  them  obtained,  such  as  riches,  authority, 
friendship,  and  good  fortune.  However  little  the 
general  position  can  help  us  in  "  searching  out "  the 
nature  of  the  various  passions,  it  shows  what  really 
is  in  Hobbes's  mind.  Since  man  is  a  desiring  animal, 
and  reaches  one  end  only  to  anticipate  further  ends, 
he  seeks  not  only  to  gratify  some  particular  passion, 
but  to  obtain  whatever  may  enable  him  to  gain  pleasure 
and  avoid  pain  of  all  kinds.  He  has  various  capacities 
for  enjoyment,  and  necessarily  desires  all  the  power 
which  may  enable  him  to  go  on  enjoying  as  much  as 
possible.  "  Favour,"  riches,  and  so  forth,  are  means 
towards  continuing  a  pleasant  life.  He  adds  a  signifi- 
cant remark :  "  And  because  the  power  of  one  man 
resisteth  and  hindereth  the  effects  of  the  power  of 


in.]  MAN  127 

another,  power  simply  is  no  more  but  the  excess  of  the 
power  of  one  above  that  of  another;  for  equal  powers 
opposed  destroy  one  another,  and  such  opposition  is 
called  contention"  It  is  clear  that  the  meaning  of 
"  power  "  has  become  restricted.  It  no  longer  means 
anything  which  enables  us  to  enjoy  or  to  secure  the 
means  of  enjoyment,  but  that  kind  of  power  which 
enables  us  to  get  a  larger  share  than  our  neighbours. 
He  is  not  thinking,  for  example,  of  the  power  of  per- 
forming on  the  lute  which  gave  him  enjoyment  when 
he  was  locked  up  in  his  bedroom,  but  of  the  power 
which  enabled  him  to  have  a  room  to  himself  and  keep 
out  the  burglars  who  might  have  knocked  him  on  the 
head.  Power  is  the  ability  of  the  individual  to  get  as 
large  a  share  as  possible  of  the  good  things  that  may 
be  going. 

He  proceeds  to  give  definitions  of  a  great  number 
of  painful  and  pleasurable  emotions.  What  we  obtain 
from  him,  however,  is  not  properly  a  general  theory 
of  the  passions,  but  a  not  very  systematic  list  of  the 
various  emotions  as  determined  by  the  relations  be- 
tween a  man  and  the  society  in  which  he  lives.  Such 
as  it  is,  however,  his  list  suggests  to  him  a  number 
of  characteristic  and  pungent  sayings  which  have  a 
bearing  upon  his  political  theory,  and  are  often,  it  must 
be  admitted,  more  forcible  than  edifying.  The  order 
of  exposition,  I  may  remark,  is  clearer  in  the  Human 
Nature  than  in  the  Leviathan. 

Since  all  desire  implies  desire  for  "power,"  the 
recognition  of  the  power  belonging  to  ourselves  or 
others  is  an  essential  element  in  our  relations  to  each 
other.  The  "acknowledgment  of  power  is  called 
" Honour"  and  to  honour  a  man  is  to  conceive  that  he 


128  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

has  an  "excess  of  power  above  him  with  whom  he 
contendeth."  All  the  signs  of  "  power  "  are  therefore 
honourable.  Beauty  of  person  or  "  general  reputation 
among  those  of  the  other  sex '  is  honourable  as  an 
indication  of  personal  vigour.  Actions  which  show 
strength  of  body,  as  victory  in  battle  or  duel,  are 
honourable.  Avoir  tue  son  homme  is  an  honour.  So 
is  a  readiness  to  great  exploits,  for  confidence  gives 
a  presumption  of  real  power ;  and  to  teach  is  honour- 
able as  a  sign  of  knowledge ;  and  riches  as  a  sign  of 
the  power  that  acquired  them  ;  and  authority  as  a  sign 
of  the  strength,  wisdom,  favour,  or  riches  by  which  it 
is  acquired.  Good  fortune  is  honourable  because  a 
sign  of  the  favour  of  God,  to  whom  is  to  be  ascribed 
all  that  cometh  to  us  by  fortune,  no  less  than  that  we 
attain  unto  by  industry.  Gravity  is  honourable  when 
a  sign  of  "  a  mind  employed  on  something  else,"  em- 
ployment being  a  sign  of  power.  It  is  dishonourable 
when  affected.  For  the  gravity  of  the  former  kind 
is  like  a  ship  laden  with  merchandise,  but  of  the  latter 
like  the  steadiness  of  a  ship  ballasted  with  sand  and 
other  trash.  Honour  is  the  manifestation  of  the  value 
we  set  on  one  another.  The  value  or  worth  of  a  man 
is,  as  of  all  other  things,  his  price :  that  is  to  say, 
as  much  as  would  be  given  for  the  use  of  his  power ; 
and  therefore  this  value  is  not  absolute,  but  a  thing 
dependent  on  the  need  and  judgment  of  another.  So  a 
good  soldier  is  more  valuable  in  war  than  in  peace,  while 
the  reverse  is  true  of  a  learned  and  uncorrupt  judge. 
As  in  other  things,  so  in  men,  not  the  seller  but  the 
buyer  determines  the  price.  For,  let  men,  as  most 
men  do,  rate  themselves  at  the  highest  value  they  can, 
yet  their  true  value  is  no  more  than  it  is  esteemed 


in.]  MAN  129 

by  others.  Moreover,  honour  consisteth  only  in  the 
opinion  of  "  power."  If  an  action  be  great  and  difficult 
and  therefore  a  proof  of  great  power,  it  matters  not 
whether  it  be  just  or  unjust.  The  ancients  thought 
they  were  honouring  their  gods  by  ascribing  to  them 
great  though  unjust  acts ;  as  in  the  Homeric  hymn, 
Mercury's  greatest  praise  is  that  "  being  born  in  the 
morning,  he  had  invented  music  at  noon,  and  before 
night  stolen  away  the  cattle  of  Apollo."  Piracy  was 
thought  honourable  by  the  Greeks,  and  at  the  present 
time  "private  duels  are  and  always  will  be  honour- 
able, though  unlawful,  till  such  time  as  there  shall  be 
honour  ordained  for  them  that  refuse,  and  ignominy 
for  them  that  make  the  challenge."  Duels  often  show 
courage,  and  therefore  "  strength  and  skill,  which  are 
power,"  though  for  the  most  part,  he  admits,  they  are 
the  effects  of  rash  speech  and  the  "  fear  of  dishonour." 
iHobbes  was  the  last  man  to  insist  that  duelling  should 
be  honoured  ;  but  that  it  was  honoured  is  indisputable, 
and  he  is  simply  considering  the  fact. 

The  desire  for  power  implies  the  desire  for  honour : 
the  recognition  of  power  by  ourselves  or  others,  for 
that  is  itself  power.  We  have  next  to  notice  the 
passions  which  correspond  to  honour.  The  first  is 
"  glory  or  'internal  gloriation  or  triumph  of  the  rnind." 
This  means  the  conception  of  our  own  power  as  com- 
pared with  the  power  of  "  him  that  contendeth  against 
us."  "  By  those  whom  it  displeaseth  this  passion  is 
called  pride ;  by  those  whom  it  pleaseth  it  is  called  a 
just  valuation  of  oneself."  When  the  "imagination  of 
our  power  "  arises  from  experience  of  our  own  actions, 
it  is  just  and  well-grounded,  and  prompts  aspiring  to 
higher  degrees  of  power.  When  it  arises  from  the 


130  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

trusting  other  people's  opinions,  it  becomes  u  false 
glory,"  and  leads  to  mistaken  ambition.  Sometimes 
glory  depends  upon  fiction,  as  when  we  imagine  our- 
selves to  be  the  hero  of  some  romance.  This  begets 
no  aspiration,  and  is  "  vain  glory '  when,  "  like  the 
fly  on  the  axletree,  a  man  exclaims,  <  What  a  dust  do 
I  raise.'  He  illustrates  it  elsewhere  from  the  gallant 
madness  of  Don  Quixote,  "  which  is  nothing  else  but 
an  expression  of  such  height  of  vain  glory  as  reading 
of  romance  may  produce  on  pusillanimous  men."  It 
is  shown  by  "  affectation  of  fashions,"  and  "  usurping 
the  signs  of  virtues  "  not  really  possessed.  The  oppo- 
site passion  to  glory  is  called  "  humility  "  by  those  by 
whom  it  is  approved,  and  by  others  "  dejection."  "  If 
well-grounded,  it  produceth  fear  to  attempt  anything 
rashly ;  if  ill,  it  utterly  cows  a  man,  that  he  neither 
dares  speak  publicly  nor  expect  success  in  any 
action." 

Another  passion  of  which  Hobbes  takes  himself  to 
have  given  the  first  explanation  is  marked  by  that 
"  distortion  of  the  countenance  which  we  call  laughter." 
The  cause  of  laughter  is  not  wit,  "  for  men  laugh  at 
mischances  and  indecencies  wherein  there  lieth  no 
wit  nor  jest  at  all."  What  moves  laughter  must  be 
something  "  new  and  unexpected."  Men,  especially 
if  "  greedy  of  applause,"  laugh  at  unexpected  success 
in  their  actions  and  at  their  own  jests.  They  laugh 
again  at  jests  which  elegantly  discover  the  absurdity 
of  another  man.  They  do  not  laugh  when  they  them- 
selves or  their  friends  are  the  objects  of  jesting. 
Laughter,  then,  is  caused  by  "  sudden  glory " :  the 
discovery  of  some  superiority  in  ourselves  to  other 
people.  The  popularity  of  this  phrase  shows,  I  fancy, 


in.]  MAN  131 

that  Hobbes  has  more  or  less  hit  the  mark.1  It  is 
only  fair  to  add  his  remark  that  the  passion  "is 
incident  most  to  them  that  are  conscious  of  the  fewest 
abilities  in  themselves  ;  who  are  forced  to  keep  them- 
selves in  their  own  favour  by  observing  the  imper- 
fections of  other  men.  And  therefore  much  laughter 
at  the  defects  of  others  is  a  sign  of  pusillanimity. 
For  of  great  minds  one  of  the  proper  works  is  to 
help  and  free  others  from  scorn,  and  compare  them- 
selves only  with  the  most  able."  We  should  only 
laugh  "when  all  the  company  may  laugh  together," 
as  "at  absurdities  abstracted  from  persons."  That 
is  a  fair  test  of  the  innocence  of  laughter,  with  which 
Chesterfield  might  agree. 

The  attempt  to  analyse  the  passions  into  some  form 
of  the  desire  for  power  or  honour  has  less  edifying 
consequences.  Hobbes,  we  discover,  is  the  most 
thoroughgoing  of  egoists,  and  not  only  admits  the 
universality  of  self-love,  but  speaks  as  though  this 
were  one  of  the  obvious  truths  which  require  no 
proof  or  explanation.  "  Pity,"  he  observes  with  super- 
lative calmness,  is  imagination  or  fiction  of  future 
calamity  to  ourselves,  proceeding  from  the  sense  of 
another  man's  calamity.  We  pity  those  who  suffer 
an  undeserved  calamity,  "  because  then  there  appeareth 
more  probability  that  the  same  may  happen  to  us : 
for  the  evil  that  liappeneth  to  an  innocent  man 
may  happen  to  every  man."  That  is  why  men  pity 
those  whom  they  love ;  for  whom  they  love  they  think 
worthy  of  good  and  therefore  not  worthy  of  calamity. 
This  may  suggest  the  question,  "What  is  the  meaning 

1  It  is  discussed  by  Professor  Sully  in  his  recent  book  upon 
humour. 


132  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

of  love  ? J;  He  discusses  this  in  the  Human  Nature, 
though  he  apparently  does  not  think  it  worthy  of  con- 
sideration in  the  Leviathan.  Love  in  the  most  general 
sense  means  simply  the  "  delight "  caused  by  an  object 
which  helps  the  vital  motion,  hatred  having  the  corre- 
sponding relation  to  pain.  This,  he  says,  sufficiently 
explains  the  love  which  men  have  to  one  another,  or 
the  pleasure  which  they  take  in  each  other's  company, 
which  entitles  them  to  be  called  "  sociable."  To  love 
men  means  that  we  think  of  them  as  useful.  Of  love 
in  the  narrower  sense,  or  the  passion  which  is  "  the 
great  theme  of  poets,"  he  observes  that,  in  spite  of 
their  "  praises,"  it  means  the  lover's  "  need,"  not  any 
special  quality  in  the  object  beloved.  "  Those  are 
most  successful  in  love  who  care  least,  which  not  per- 
ceiving many  men  cast  away  their  services  as  one  arrow 
after  another  till,  in  the  end,  together  with  their  hopes 
they  lose  their  wits."  Hobbes  is  not  very  clear  at  this 
point  —  perhaps  he  was  a  little  shy  of  "  the  poets  "  — 
but  he  does  not  appear  to  take  a  romantic  view  of  the 
question.  Another  variety  of  love  is  more  properly 
called  "  good  will  or  charity."  This  is  a  modification, 
again,  of  the  desire  for  power.  Nothing  can  convince 
a  man  of  his  own  power  more  completely  than  the 
discovery  that  he  is  able  not  only  to  accomplish  his 
own  desires  but  also  to  assist  other  men  in  theirs. 
This  is  the  secret  of  "  the  natural  affection  of  parents  to 
their  children  (which  the  Greeks  call  crropy^),"  as  also 
of  the  affection  implied  in  "  assisting  those  who  adhere 
to  us."  When,  however,  men  bestow  benefits  upon 
strangers,  they  do  not  act  from  charity  ;  but  either 
seek  to  "  purchase  f riendship  J:  by  contract,  or  seek 
peace  from  fear.  We  act  for  the  good  of  others,  it 


in,]  MAN 

seems,  either  from  the  complacency  derived  from 
the  evidence  of  our  own  power,  which  is  properly 
"  charity/'  or  in  order  to  buy  their  services.  Hobbes 
speaks  as  if  his  view  were  not  only  obvious,  but 
edifying  —  as  though  he  were  simply  elaborating  St. 
Paul's  famous  description  of  the  Christian  virtue  of 
charity. 

Another  passion  is  more  intelligible  to  him.  Since 
"  knowledge  is  power,"  we  naturally  desire  to  extend 
our  knowledge.  The  corresponding  passion  is  called 
"  admiration,"  and  the  "  appetite  "  is  "  curiosity."  Its 
existence,  like  the  faculty  of  language,  marks  the  point 
at  which  we  part  company  from  beasts.  The  beast 
flies  from  or  approaches  a  new  object,  only  considering 
whether  it  will  "  serve  his  turn."  The  man  endeavours 
to  discover  the  cause.  Hence  arises  all  philosophy, 
which  is,  as  we  know,  the  theory  of  consequences  in 
general.  A  man  in  chase  of  riches  or  power  ("which 
in  respect  of  knowledge  are  but  sensuality  ")  does  not 
care  about  the  motions  of  the  stars :  it  is  only  a  few, 
as  he  remarks  elsewhere,  who  appreciate  science,  "  for 
science  is  of  that  nature  as  none  can  understand  it  to 
be,  except  such  as  in  a  good  measure  have  attained 
unto  it."  The  military  arts  are  of  obvious  utility  and 
their  possessors  are  powerful.  "  Though  the  true 
mother  of  them  be  science,  namely  the  mathematics; 
yet  because  they  are  brought  into  light  by  the  hand  of 
the  artificer,  they  be  esteemed  (the  mid-wife  passing 
with  the  vulgar  for  the  mother)  as  his  issue."  Hobbes 
can  preach  with  feeling  on  the  superiority  of  philo- 
sophical inquiry  to  the  mere  bread-winning  studies. 
Meanwhile  "  curiosity  is  delight ;  therefore  also 
novelty  is  so;  but  especially  that  novelty  from  which 


134  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

a  man  coiiceiveth  an  opinion  true  or  false  of  bettering 
his  estate ;  for  in  such  case  they  stand  affected  with 
the  hope  that  all  gamesters  have  while  the  cards  are 
shuffling."  That  no  doubt  expresses  a  very  genuine 
sentiment.  Though  science  is  power,  he  would  say, 
the  man  of  science  has  very  little  honour,  unless  he 
can  apply  his  science  to  generally  intelligible  ends. 
"  Curiosity  "  and  reason  distinguish  man  from  beasts ; 
"  which  makes  me,  when  I  hear  a  man  upon  the  dis- 
covery of  any  new  and  ingenious  knowledge  or  inven- 
tion ask  gravely,  that  is  to  say  scornfully,  what  'tis 
good  for,  meaning  what  money  it  will  bring  in,  to 
esteem  that  man  not  sufficiently  removed  from, 
brutality."  Love  of  philosophic  truth,  one  is  glad  to 
observe,  appears  to  Hobbes  to  be  admirable  for  itself, 
though  perhaps  at  some  cost  of  consistency. 

The  curious  argument  which  follows  is  of  some 
interest.  What,  he  asks,  is  the  cause  of  the  great 
difference  between  men's  capacities  ?  It  cannot  be  a 
difference  in  the  "  natural  temper  of  the  brain,"  for,  if 
so,  the  difference  would  show  itself  "  in  the  senses  " ; 
whereas  wise  men  and  foolish  have  (as  he  assumes) 
equal  senses.  Imagination  being  "  decaying  sense," 
the  imagination  ought  to  be  equal.  The  difference  is 
therefore  owing  to  the  differences  in  the  constitution 
"  of  the  body."  What  helps  the  "  vital  constitution  '• 
in  one  man,  and  is  therefore  pleasurable,  hinders  it  in 
another,  and  is  therefore  painful.  He  discusses  the 
"  intellectual  virtues ';  —  meaning,  the  qualities  which 
are  desired  "  for  eminence  "  and  are  gauged  by  "  com- 
parison"; for  "if  all  things  were  equal  in  all  men, 
nothing  would  be  prized."  The  great  difference 
between  men's  wits  is  due  to  a  difference  in  "  quick- 


m.]  MAN  135 

ness,"  or  "  swift  succession  of  one  thought  to 
another/'  and  in  "  steadiness  of  direction  to  some 
approved  end."  A  defect  of  quickness  is  "  dullness  or 
stupidity  "  ;  and  the  difference  is  due  to  the  difference 
of  the  passions.  Desire  for  power,  riches,  knowledge, 
or  honour  (the  last  three  being  modifications  of  the 
first)  is  thus  the  great  cause  of  the  "  difference  of  wit." 
A  man  who  has  no  great  passion  for  any  of  these  things 
may  be  good  in  the  sense  of  inoffensive ;  "  yet  he  can- 
not possibly  have  either  a  great  fancy  or  much  judg- 
ment. For  the  thoughts  are  to  the  desires  as  scouts 
and  spies,  to  range  abroad  and  find  the  way  to  the 
things  desired —  all  steadiness  of  the  mind's  motion  and 
all  quickness  of  the  same  proceeding  from  thence  ;  for 
as  to  have  no  desire  is  to  be  dead,  so  to  have  weak 
passions  is  dullness ;  and  to  have  passions  indifferently 
for  everything  is  giddiness  and  distraction  " ;  while 
abnormal  vehemence  of  passion  is  madness.  That 
intellectual  excellence  is  dependent  upon  the  character 
and  the  strength  of  the  emotions  is  a  doctrine  upon 
which  Hobbes  rightly  and  impressively  insists.  Fancy, 
according  to  him,  means  quickness  in  perceiving  "  simili- 
tudes," and  judgment  or  "discretion"  quickness  in  per- 
ceiving "dissimilitudes."  Fancy  must  be  "eminent" 
in  poetry,  though  judgment  is  required ;  while  in  his- 
tory fancy  is  wanted  only  to  "  adorn  the  style."  In 
demonstration,  "judgment  does  all,"  except  that  "an 
apt  similitude  "  may  be  required  to  open  the  under- 
standing. "  Discretion  "  is  required  in  poetry ;  an  "  an- 
atomist or  physician  "  may  speak  of  "  unclean  things  "  ; 
"  but  for  another  man  to  write  his  extravagant  or 
pleasant  fancies  of  the  same  is  as  if  a  man  from  being 
tumbled  in  the  dirt  should  come  and  present  himself 


136  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

before  good  company."  This  is  a  doctrine  for  which 
Hobbes  might  have  found  plenty  of  contemporary 
and  other  illustrations.  An  excessive  "mobility  of 
mind,"  again,  maketh  men  depart  "from  their  dis- 
course by  a  parenthesis,  and  from  that  parenthesis  by 
another,  till  at  length  they  either  lose  themselves,  or 
make  their  narration  like  a  dream  or  some  studied 
nonsense."  He  would  not  have  enjoyed  Sordello. 
"  Madness  "  is  a  general  name  for  "  all  passions  that 
produce  strange  and  unusual  behaviour."  It  is  espe- 
cially conspicuous  in  a  multitude,  he  says,  answering  by 
anticipation  a  famous  query  of  Bishop  Butler.  "  For 
what  argument  of  madness  can  there  be  greater  than  to 
clamour,  strike,  and  throw  stones  at  our  best  friends  ? 
Yet  this  is  somewhat  less  than  such  a  multitude  will  do. 
For  they  will  clamour,  fight  against  and  destroy  those 
by  whom  all  their  lifetime  before  they  have  been  pro- 
tected and  secured  from  injury.  And  if  this  be  mad- 
ness in  the  multitude,  it  is  the  same  in  every  particular 
man."  Each  particle  of  water  "contributes  as  much 
to  the  roaring  of  the  sea"  as  any  other  drop,  and  the 
same  is  true  of  the  "seditious  roaring  of  a  troubled 
nation." 

Such  remarks,  though  characteristic,  are  more  or 
less  digressions  from  the  main  purpose,  to  which  he 
returns  in  a  chapter  upon  "  the  difference  of  manners ': 
in  the  Leviathan.  By  manners,  he  tells  us,  he  does  not 
mean  "  points  of  the  small  morals  "  —  social  etiquette  — 
but  the  qualities  of  mankind  that  concern  their  living 
together  in  "peace  and  unity."  In  other  words,  he 
will  ask  how  the  passions  of  the  individual  bear  upon 
the  political  order.  Since  felicity,  as  we  have  seen, 
"  is  a  continual  progress  of  the  desire  from  one  object 


in.]  MAN  137 

to  the  other,"  all  men  desire  both  to  procure  and 
assure  a  contented  life.  Unluckily  they  differ  as  to 
the  way,  from  the  diversity  of  passions  or  difference 
in  knowledge.  In  the  first  place,  therefore,  he  will 
"put  for  a  general  inclination  of  all  mankind,  a  per- 
petual and  restless  desire  of  power  after  power,  that 
endeth  only  in  death."  It  is  not  that  a  man  can 
always  hope  for  a  greater  delight,  but  because  he  can- 
not be  assured  of  "  the  means  to  live  which  he  hath 
at  present  without  the  acquisition  of  more."  "  Com- 
petition of  riches,  honour,  command,  or  other  power 
inelineth  to  contention,  enmity,  and  war ;  because  the 
way  of  one  competitor  to  the  attaining  of  his  desire  is 
to  kill,  subdue,  supplant,  or  repel  the  other."  Par- 
ticularly "  competition  of  praise  (as  he  rather  oddly 
adds)  inelineth  to  a  reverence  of  antiquity.  For  men 
contend  with  the  living,  not  with  the  dead ;  to  these 
ascribing  more  than  due,  that  they  may  obscure  the 
glory  of  the  other."  Desire  of  "  ease  "  disposeth  men 
to  obedience,  and  so  does  desire  of  knowledge  and  the 
arts  of  peace,  for  such  desire  "  containeth  a  desire  of 
leisure."  Desire  of  fame  "  disposeth  to  laudable  actions," 
even  of  "  fame  after  death."  For  though  after  death 
we  have  no  sense  of  praise  on  earth,  men  have  a 
present  delight  therein  from  foresight  of  it,  and  of 
the  benefit  to  their  posterity ;  which  though  they  see 
not,  yet  they  "  imagine,"  and  everything  that  is  a 
pleasure  to  the  sense,  the  same  also  is  pleasure  in  the 
imagination.  Receiving  benefits  from  an  equal  "  dis- 
poseth to  counterfeit  love,  but  really  secret  hatred  ; 
and  puts  a  man  into  the  estate  of  a  desperate  debtor 
that,  in  declining  the  sight  of  his  creditor,  tacitly 
wishes  him  there  where  he  might  never  see  him  more. 


138  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

For  benefits  oblige,  and  obligation  is  thraldom ;  and 
an  unrequitable  obligation  perpetual  thraldom,  which 
is  to  one's  equal  hateful.''  Obligation  to  a  recognised 
superior,  however,  "inclines  to  love,"  for  it  can  be 
requited  by  gratitude,  and  so  long  as  there  is  a  hope 
of  requital,  we  are  disposed  to  love  even  an  equal 
or  inferior  benefactor ;  the  obligation  is  then  mutual ; 
"  from  whence  proceedeth  an  emulation  of  who  shall 
exceed  in  benefiting;  the  most  noble  and  profitable 
contention  possible ;  wherein  the  victor  is  pleased 
with  his  victory,  and  the  other  revenged  by  confessing 
it."  Ignorance  "  disposeth  men  to  take  on  trust  not 
only  the  truth  they  know  not,  but  also  the  errors  and, 
which  is  more,  the  nonsense  of  them  they  trust." 
Ignorance  of  the  nature  of  right,  in  particular,  "  dis- 
poseth a  man  to  think  that  unjust  which  it  hath  been 
the  custom  to  punish,  and  that  just,  of  the  impunity 
and  approbation  whereof  they  can  produce  an  example 
or,  as  the  lawyers,  which  only  use  this  false  measure  of 
justice,  barbarously  call  it  a  precedent."  Such  men  " set 
themselves  against  reason  as  often  as  reason  is  against 
them;  which  is  the  cause  that  the  doctrine  of  right 
and  wrong  is  perpetually  disputed  both  by  the  pen 
and  the  sword ;  whereas  the  doctrine  of  lines  and 
figures  is  not  so."  Truth  in  geometry  "  crosses  no 
man's  ambition,  profit,  or  lust."  "For  I  doubt  not  but 
if  it  had  been  a  thing  contrary  to  any  man's  right  of 
dominion,  or  to  the  interest  of  men  that  have  dominion, 
that  the  three  angles  of  a  triangle  should  be  equal  to  two 
angles  of  a  square,  that  doctrine  should  have  been,  if  not 
disputed,  yet  by  the  burning  of  all  books  of  geometry 
suppressed,  as  far  as  he  whom  it  concerned  was 
able." 


in.]  MAN  139 

The  quaint  passage  in  the  Human  Nature  which 
concludes  this  account  of  the  passions  sums  up  his 
view.  Life,  he  says,  may  be  compared  to  a  race  — 
a  race  which  has  no  other  "  goal "  or  "  garland  "  than 
"being  foremost."  "  In  it  to  endeavour  is  appetite;  to 
be  remiss  is  sensuality:  to  consider  them  behind  is 
glory :  to  consider  them  before  is  humility :  ...  to  fall 
on  the  sudden  is  disposition  to  weep :  to  see  another 
fall  is  disposition  to  laugh :  to  see  one  outgone  whom 
we  would  not  is  pity:  to  see  one  outgo  whom  we 
would  not  is  indignation :  to  hold  fast  by  another  is 
love:  to  carry  him  on  that  so  holdeth  is  charity:  to 
hurt  oneself  for  haste  is  shame :  .  .  .  continually  to  be 
outgone  is  misery :  continually  to  outgo  the  next  before 
is  felicity :  and  to  forsake  the  course  is  to  die." 

Life,  we  see,  is  essentially  competition,  though  as 
yet  the  struggle  for  existence  is  regarded  as  only 
affecting  the  individual.  Hobbes,  it  will  probably 
appear  to  most  people,  takes  a  sufficiently  cynical  view 
of  human  nature.  He  has  been  compared  to  Roche- 
foucauld, though  he  does  not  represent  the  epigram- 
matic skill  which  is  gained  in  highly  polished  society. 
He  has  frequented  Mersenne's  "cell,"  not  the  courtier's 
salon.  His  opinions  might  be  compared  to  the  so-called 
Machiavellianism  of  Bacon's  essays  — the  concentration 
of  the  experience  of  the  statesman  and  lawyer,  who 
wishes  to  see  things  as  they  are  and  to  get  rid  of 
humbug  and  conventional  gloss.  Hobbes,  however, 
has  a  more  distinctly  scientific  aim,  and  wishes  at  least 
to  connect  his  remarks  with  psychological  theory.  He 
would  defend  himself  against  the  charge  that  he  is  tak- 
ing an  "unworthy"  view  of  mankind  by  appealing  to 
plain  facts.  Men,  he  would  say,  are  stupid  and  selfish. 


140  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

That,  no  doubt,  is  not  the  way  to  be  popular.  The 
"  idealist "  often  takes  a  more  painful  view  of  men  as 
they  are,  than  the  poor  "  cynic  " ;  but  he  atones  for  it 
by  an  enthusiastic  view  of  what  they  may  become,  and 
his  readers  catch  the  contagion  of  his  enthusiasm. 
Their  perception  of  the  general  corruption  convinces 
them  that  they  at  any  rate  are  of  the  salt  of  the  earth, 
and  this  is  comforting.  If  Hobbes's  cynicism  meant 
simply  that  he  recognised  the  great  part  played  by 
dullness  and  selfishness  in  human  affairs,  and  the 
futility  of  overlooking  that  fact  in  political  theories, 
we  might  say  that  he  was  applying  a  wholesome 
corrective  to  extravagant  belief  in  millenniums. 

It  must  be  granted,  however,  that  he  goes  beyond 
this.  His  quiet  resolution  of  all  the  virtues  into  forms 
of  egoism  was  of  course  condemned  by  the  respectable. 
In  our  eyes  it  may  be  redeemed  by  the  charming 
simplicity  and  utter  unconsciousness  of  offence  with 
which  he  propounds  his  atrocious  theories.  He  be- 
comes unintentionally  humorous.  We  must,  how- 
ever, notice  the  nature  of  the  reasoning  which  leads 
him  to  such  conclusions.  That  is  implied  by  one 
characteristic  doctrine.  Every  man,  he  says,  calls  that 
which  pleaseth  him.  good,  and  that  which  displeaseth 
him  evil.  Since  men  differ  in  "  constitution,"  they 
differ  as  to  what  is  good  and  what  is  evil.  There  is 
no  such  thing  as  "  absolute  goodness  considered  with- 
out relation."  Even  God's  goodness  means  his  good- 
ness to  us.  The  words  "good"  and  "evil,"  he  says 
elsewhere,  "  are  ever  used  with  reference  to  us."  No 
"  common  rule  "  can  be  taken  "  from  the  nature  of  the 
objects  themselves."  Such  a  rule  must  be  made  by 
the  man  himself,  or  by  the  "  commonwealth,"  or  by 


in.]  MAN  141 

some  arbitrator  set  up  by  consent.  It  is  indeed  quite 
clear  that  from  Hobbes's  point  of  view  the  abstract 
words  "  good J;  and  "  evil ':  could  have  no  meaning. 
As  "  man  "  only  means  John  and  Thomas  and  Peter,  j 
"  good  "  only  means  what  John  and  Thomas  and  Peter 
like,  and  "  evil '  what  they  dislike.  Moreover,  if 
psychological  and  ethical  theories  are  to  be  based  upon 
experience,  we  must  begin  by  studying  the  likings  and 
dislikings  of  human  beings.  Science  must  start  from 
the  actual,  not  from  the  ideal.  [A  scientific  theory  of 
human  nature  begins  from  the  question,  what  passions 
do  in  fact  govern,  not  from  the  question  what  passions 
ought  to  govern,  human  beings. '  Now  in  fact  men 
have  various  passions  and  desires  which  lead  them  to 
break  as  well  as  to  obey  rules  of  morality.  In  a 
dozen  men  we  may  find  a  Judas  Iscariot  as  well  as  a 
St.  John ;  and  we  have  to  account  equally  for  both. 
As  a  physiologist  has  to  deal  with  the  morbid  as  well 
as  the  healthy,  so  the  psychologist  has  to  deal  with 
the  traitor  as  well  as  the  saint,  and  with  all  the  com- 
plex play  of  good  and  bad  impulses,  which  make  saints 
and  criminals  and  men  of  every  intervening  shade. 
He  will  of  course  admit  that,  as  a  fact,  a  certain  moral 
code  comes  into  existence,  conformity  to  which  is 
regarded  with  approval  by  the  average  man.  How  it 
comes  to  be  formed,  and  what  is  the  nature  of  its 
authority,  are  questions  to  which  Hobbes  addresses 
himself  in  the  political  treatises,  and  of  which  he  offers 
a  very  remarkable  solution. 

Hobbes  can  only  say  at  present,  that  since  each 
man  is  governed  by  his  own  passions  and  desires, 
the  formation  of  the  "common  rule'  supposes  some 
"  arbitrator "  or  central  authority.  His  uncompro- 


142  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

mising  egoism  is  an  inevitable  consequence  of  his 
position.  It  is  assumed  by  the  moralists  whom  he 
attacked  that  there  is  some  ultimate  and  absolute 
good:  an  ideal  law  revealed  through  reason  and 
equally  binding  upon  all  men.  It  determines  con- 
duct, since  the  will  always  chooses  the  "apparent 
good."  Reason  is  itself  virtue,  and  vice  means  igno- 
rance, for  it  is  only  from  a  mistaken  view  of  what  is 
really  good  that  men  fail  to  do  right.  Hobbes  might 
agree  with  the  doctrine  that  man  always  chooses  the 
apparent  good;  but  he  denies  that  the  really  good  is 
knowable.  The  doctrine  therefore  means  for  him 
that  each  man  will  do  what  is  pleasant  to  himself. 
He  is  governed  exclusively  by  his  own  desires,  and  it 
would  be  as  absurd  to  speak  of  a  man  acting  from 
another  man's  motives  as  to  speak  of  his  body  being 
nourished  by  another  man's  food.  Now  it  must  be 
observed  that  later  thinkers,  who  profess  equally  to 
base  ethical  theories  entirely  upon  experience,  will  not 
admit  this  conclusion.  They  hold  that  sympathy  is  a 
genuine  and  ultimate  emotion;  and  that  man  can  so 
identify  himself  with  the  society  of  which  he  forms  a 
part,  that  public  spirit  or  patriotism  or  philanthropy 
or  family  affection  may  be  as  genuine  a  motive  as  the 
animal  appetites.  They  hold,  and,  as  I  think,  rightly, 
that  an  empirical  theory  of  morality  does  not  really 
involve  the  acceptance  of  a  selfish  or  egoistic  doctrine. 
But  it  is  undeniable  that  this  interpretation  is  plausible. 
The  utilitarians  could  argue  with  great  force  that  a 
tendency  to  produce  the  "  greatest  happiness  of  the 
greatest  number  "  gives  the  true  criterion  of  morality. 
But  as  an  historical  fact,  they  found  their  greatest 
difficulty  in  reconciling  this  with  their  other  assump- 


in.]  MAN  14^ 

tion,  that  each  man  seeks  his  own  happiness.  They 
tried  to  explain  "  altruism '  by  "  association,"  at  the 
risk  of  making  it  a  kind  of  desirable  fallacy,  or  else 
they  tried  to  show  —  what  unfortunately  cannot  be 
shown — that  self-sacrifice  is  always  repaid,  or,  in  other 
words,  is  a  sham  sacrifice. 

Hobbes  had  not  to  bother  himself  about  such  con- 
ciliation. He  was  perfectly  content  to  profess  the 
most  unblushing  egoism  and  carry  it  out  consistently. 
His  essential  aim  was  to  be  scientific,  to  accept  the 
obvious  facts,  and  to  carry  out  the  conclusions  logi- 
cally. His  nominalism  naturally  went  with  individual- 
ism. Each  man  obviously  is  a  separate  thing  which 
must  be  explained  by  its  own  properties,  and  not  by 
reference  to  any  mysterious  bond  of  unity  with  other 
things.  Unfortunately  there  is  selfishness  enough  in 
the  world  to  give  much  plausibility  to  some  of  his 
statements,  and  to  admit  of  their  being  often  approxi- 
mately true.  Finally,  his  thorough  materialism  seems 
to  make  the  assumption  of  selfishness  inevitable.  If, 
indeed,  it  be  possible  to  regard  man  as  a  mere  mechan- 
ism, worked  by  the  laws  of  motion,  and  yet  to  regard 
him  as  a  self-conscious,  reasoning,  and  remembering 
animal,  it  may  also  be  possible  to  regard  him  as 
sympathetic  and  unselfish.  Still  it  is  difficult  to  see 
how  the  actions  of  a  mere  automaton  affected  only  by 
the  pressure  of  bodies  in  contact  with  him,  can  be 
really  determined  by  the  conditions  of  other  automata. 
He  may  be  so  constituted  as  to  preserve  his  own 
equilibrium ;  but  his  relation  to  his  like  would  seem 
to  be  limited  to  the  cases  in  which  two  automata  knock 
their  heads  together.  Hobbes,  however,  had  no  diffi- 
culty in  altogether  denying  the  existence  of  sympathy. 


144  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

The  desire  for  self-preservation  was  quite  enough  to 
provide  the  working  force  for  his  scheme ;  and  he 
propounds  his  theory  with  the  straightforward  blunt- 
ness  which  has  the  charm  of  obvious  sincerity. 

2.    Theology 

We  are  now  pretty  well  prepared  to  proceed  to  the 
third  part  of  Hobbes's  philosophy;  but  there  are  two 
other  applications  of  his  first  principles  which  have  a 
bearing  upon  his  political  doctrine,  and  which  also 
deserve  consideration  for  themselves.  We  have  seen 
what  Hobbes  thought  of  bodies  ;  we  may  ask  what  was 
his  creed  as  to  the  creator  of  bodies  and  the  relation 
of  the  creator  to  man  ?  His  arguments  upon  theology 
and  upon  the  problem  of  free-will  excited  the  keenest 
antagonism  among  his  contemporaries.  His  position 
in  both  cases  is  remarkable,  if  only  as  illustrating  the 
stir  which  he  gave  to  thought  in  general.  Whether 
his  teaching  was  right  or  wrong,  or  a  little  of  both,  it 
at  least  caused  his  opponents  to  look  into  the  founda- 
tions of  their  own  creed. 

Hobbes  steadily  denied  that  the  name  "  atheist ': 
properly  applied  to  him.  He  calls  himself  not  only  a 
theist,  but  a  Christian,  and  even  a  faithful  member  of 
the  Church  of  England.  Some  of  his  critics  accept 
his  assurances  so  far  as  to  hold  that  he  only  meant  to 
reject  scholastic  dogmas  or  "incrustations,"  and  did 
not  get  beyond  what  is  vaguely  called  Socinianism,  or, 
perhaps,  "  unsectarian  Christianity."  Tn  such  discus- 
sions two  distinct  questions  are  apt  to  be  confounded. 
The  question,  that  is,  what  a  man  really  believed,  is 
identified  with  the  question  what  were  the  logical  conse- 


in.]  MAN  146 

quences  of  his  belief.  It  is  undeniable  that  a  man  often 
rejects,  and  sometimes  rejects  with  horror,  doctrines 
which  to  others  seem  to  be  inevitable  inferences  from 
the  first  principles  which  he  explicitly  affirms.  It  is 
therefore  "  unfair,"  we  are  told,  to  attribute  to  a  man 
the  beliefs  which,  to  our  minds,  he  was  logically  bound 
to  hold.  It  is  certainly  unfair  so  far  as  it  is  false.  If  a 
man  repudiates  a  doctrine,  the  repudiation  should  be 
noted,  even  though  we  may  think  that  he  is  under  a 
delusion,  which  amounts  to  a  concealment  of  his  own 
opinions  from  himself  under  a  jugglery  of  words. 
Sometimes,  indeed,  we  are  only  "unfair  "  in  the  sense 
that  we  are  paying  him  too  high  a  compliment  by 
supposing  that  he  saw  the  full  bearing  of  his  argu- 
ments. It  is  no  doubt  unfair  again  to  impute  opinions 
which  a  man  disavows,  when  they  are  opinions  which 
will  incur  odium,  or  perhaps  involve  a  probability  of 
being  burnt.  If  the  bishops,  of  whom  Hobbes  was 
afraid,  had  refused  to  take  notice  of  his  repudiation  of 
atheism,  they  would  certainly  have  been  unjust.  We 
have  not  now,  however,  to  consider  whether  Hobbes 
deserved  either  burning  or  damnation.  The  devoutest 
of  bishops  would  not  have  the  least  wish  to  burn 
him  at  the  present  day,  and  we  generally  admit  that 
opinions,  honestly  entertained  for  their  supposed  reason- 
ableness, do  not  justify  moral  reprobation.  Our  duty 
to  Hobbes  personally  is  simply  the  duty  of  ascertain- 
ing what,  as  a  fact,  he  did  think,  or  thought  that  he 
thought.  It  is  of  some  importance  to  know  what  he 
thought  if  we  wish  to  estimate  his  character  for 
honesty  and  courage.  But  for  us  the  more  important 
question  is  what  were  the  true  logical  bearings  of  his 
position,  whether  he  perceived  them  or  not.  Those 


146  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

were  what  really  affected  the  thought  of  his  time. 
When  you  have  once  started  an  argument,  you  cannot 
tell  what  effect  it  will  have  upon  others.  You  are 
firing  a  charge  of  dynamite,  and  the  explosion  will  act 
irrespectively  of  the  man  who  set  it  going.  The  first 
and  most  important  question  is  what  "  Hobbism r 
means,  whether  Hobbes  meant  it  or  not.  When  we 
know  that,  we  can  draw  such  inferences  as  seem 
reasonable  as  to  his  personal  character. 

In  his  Objections  to  Descartes,  Hobbes  indicates 
very  plainly  his  position  in  regard  to  theology.  He 
criticises Descartes' s famous  argument  that  the  "idea" 
of  God  as  a  perfect  being  necessarily  implies  also 
God's  existence.  Hobbes  replies  summarily  that  we 
have  no  "  idea  "  of  God.  An  idea  according  to  him  is, 
as  we  have  seen,  nothing  but  "  decaying  sense."  It  is 
a  fading  picture  of  some  object  previously  perceived 
by  the  hands,  eyes,  or  ears.  Now  nobody,  of  course, 
could  ever  have  supposed  that  "  God  "  could  be  per- 
ceived in  that  way.  Descartes  answers  that  by 
"  idea "  he  means  something  entirely  different  from 
Hobbes's  "  idea."  What  he  meant  need  not  be  inquired, 
and  Hobbes  did  not  take  the  trouble  to  inquire.  He 
takes  it  for  granted  that  all  knowledge  of  facts  comes 
to  us  through  the  senses,  and  that  the  a  priori  method 
without  appeal  to  experiences  must  be  sterile.  That 
is  to  him  too  obvious  to  need  proof.  If  so,  it  would 
seem  that  demonstrations  of  the  existence  of  God  are 
impossible.  "  Knowable  "  means  visible  or  tangible, 
and  God  is  admittedly  neither.  Hobbes,  however, 
does  not  admit  this  conclusion.  After  discussing 
man's  knowledge  and  passions  as  related  to  "  natural 
things,"  he  assumes  that  we  also  give  names  to  (that 


in.]  MAN  147 

is,  reason  about)  "  things  supernatural,"  that  is  God 
and  spirits.  Such  names  ought  to  correspond  to  some 
reality,  and  their  meaning  will  explain  in  what  sense 
we  use  the  phrases  ascribing  certain  attributes  to  the 
beings  named.  The  belief  in  things  supernatural  is 
produced  by  "curiosity,'7  that  is,  as  he  explains,  "love 
of  the  knowledge  of  causes."  This  leads  a  man  to  ask 
the  cause  of  an  effect ;  "  and,  again,  the  cause  of  that 
cause ;  till  of  necessity  he  must  come  to  this  thought 
at  last  that  there  is  some  cause,  whereof  there  is  no 
former  cause,  but  is  eternal ;  which  is  it  men  call  God; 
so  that  it  is  impossible  to  make  any  profound  inquiry 
into  natural  causes,  without  being  inclined  thereby  to 
believe  there  is  one  God  eternal."  God  is  the  first 
"  power  of  all  powers,  and  first  cause  of  all  causes." 
The  name  implies  "  eternity,  incomprehensibility,  and 
omnipotency."  Incomprehensibility  is  explained  by 
an  analogy.  A  man  born  blind,  when  he  warms  him- 
self by  the  fire,  may  convince  himself  that  there  is 
something  there  which  is  called  fire  by  his  companions, 
and  which  is  the  cause  of  the  heat  which  he  feels. 
But  he  cannot  have  any  such  "  idea  r}  of  it  as  those 
have  that  see  it.  "  So  also  by  the  visible  things  in 
this  world,  and  their  admirable  order,  a  man  may 
conceive  there  is  a  cause  of  them,  which  men  call  God, 
and  yet  not  have  an  idea  or  image  of  him  in  his  mind." 
The  attributes  of  this  Being  must  also  be  inconceiv- 
able. We  speak  of  God  as  "  seeing,  hearing,  speaking, 
knowing,  loving,  and  the  like,"  names  which  have  a 
meaning  as  applied  to  men,  but  mean  "  nothing  in  the 
nature  of  God."  It  is  "  well  reasoned,  shall  not  the 
God  that  made  the  eye  see,  and  the  ear  hear  ? '  But 
it  is  also  well  reasoned  "  if  we  say,  shall  God  which 


148  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

made  the  eye,  not  see  without  the  eye;  or  that  made 
the  ear,  nor  hear  without  the  ear ;  or  that  made  the 
brain,  not  know  without  the  brain ;  or  that  made  the 
heart,  not  love  without  the  heart."  The  attributes  of 
God  signify  "  our  incapacity '  or  "  our  reverence  "  : 
our  "incapacity  when  we  say  incomprehensible  and 
infinite;  our  reverence  when  we  give  him  those  names 
which  amongst  us  are  the  names  of  those  things  we 
most  magnify  and  commend,  as  omnipotent,  omni- 
scient, just,  merciful,  etc." 

This  may  remind  us  of  many  controversies  in  which 
some  orthodox  divines  have  agreed  with  Hobbes.  It 
recalls,  for  example,  the  agnosticism  which  Mr.  Her- 
bert Spencer  professes  himself  to  have  expanded  from 
Sir  William  Hamilton  5  while  Mansel  used  the  same 
doctrine  in  defence  of  orthodox  creeds.  So  far 
Hobbes  might  have  agreed  with  Mansel  rather  than 
with  Mr.  Spencer,  and  might  have  believed  his  creed 
to  be  susceptible  of  an  interpretation  reconcilable 
with  orthodoxy.  His  position,  however,  depends 
upon  his  theory  of  causation.  Although  he  speaks 
of  the  "  admirable  order  "  of  the  world,  he  emphati- 
cally rejects  the  doctrine  of  final  causes.  We  are  not 
to  infer  from  the  eye  or  the  ear  any  likeness  between 
the  Creator  and  his  creature ;  but  only  some  inscruta- 
ble cause.  And  if  we  take  into  account  what  Hobbes 
meant  by  cause  we  come  to  a  difficulty.  The  whole 
"  world-process,"  according  to  him,  is  simply  a  series 
of  changes  in  motion :  when  we  inquire  into  the  cause 
of  any  event  we  are  really  asking  what  was  the  pre- 
vious state  of  things  from  which  the  succeeding  was 
developed  by  a  continuous  series  of  change  accord- 
ing to  purely  mechanical  laws.  The  "cause"1  of  the 


in.]  MAN  149 

present  arrangement  of  the  stars  is  simply  their  pre- 
ceding arrangement.  The  argument,  therefore,  for  a 
first  cause  means,  on  his  interpretation,  that  we  can- 
not continue  this  inquiry  indefinitely.  Instead  of 
saying  "this  state  implies  a  preceding  state,"  we 
must  say  "  this  state  implies  that  it  was  put  together 
super  naturally . ' ' 

Now  in  the  De  Corpore  he  criticises  this  argument 
himself.  A  man  will  be  "  wearied,"  he  says,  in  tracing 
back  the  series  of  cause  and  effect,  and  "  give  over ?; 
inquiry.  "  But  whether  we  suppose  the  world  to  be 
finite  or  infinite,  no  absurdity  will  follow."  "  As  it  is 
true  that  nothing  is  moved  by  itself,  so  it  is  true  also 
that  nothing  is  moved  but  by  that  which  was  already 
moved."  That  implies  an  indefinite  regress.  "  I  can- 
not therefore  commend,"  he  says,  "those  that  boast 
they  have  demonstrated  by  reasons  drawn  from  natural 
things  that  the  world  had  a  beginning.  They  are  con- 
temned by  idiots  because  they  understand  them  not ; 
and  by  the  learned,  because  they  understand  them ; 
by  both  deservedly."  "  They  are  entangled,"  he  says, 
"  in  the  words  infinite  and  eternal,  of  which  we  have 
in  our  mind  110  idea  but  that  of  our  own  insufficiency  to 
comprehend  them,"  and  thus  they  are  forced  "  either 
to  speak  something  absurd,  or,  which  they  love  worse, 
to  hold  their  peace."  Infinite,  in  short,  means  simply 
indefinitely  great.  Hobbes,  therefore,  will  be  content 
'<  with  that  doctrine  concerning  the  beginning  and 
magnitude  of  the  world  which  I  have  been  persuaded 
to  by  the  Holy  Scriptures,  and  fame  of  the  miracles 
which  confirm  them ;  and  by  the  custom  of  my  coun- 
try and  reverence  due  to  the  laws." 

These   may   be   excellent,   but   are   scarcely  philo- 


150  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

sophical  reasons.  Bramhall,  when  he  accused  Hobbes 
of  atheism,  refers  to  this  passage.  Hobbes,  he  says, 
denies  that  there  is  any  "  argument  to  prove  a  Deity," 
except  the  creation  of  the  world,  and  that  the  question 
whether  the  world  had  a  beginning  must  be  settled 
"  not  by  argument,  but  by  the  magistrate's  authority." 
Hobbes  replies  that  it  may  be  settled  "  by  the  Scrip- 
tures." "  As  far  as  arguments  from  natural  reason," 
he  adds,  "  neither  you  nor  any  other  have  hitherto 
brought  any,  except  the  creation,  that  has  not  made 
it  more  doubtful  to  many  men  than  it  was  before." 
He  then  repeats  the  passage  just  quoted  from  the 
De  Corpore,  and  adds  :  —  "  This,  doctor,  is  not  ill  said, 
and  yet  it  is  all  you  ground  your  slander  on,  which 
you  make  to  sneak  vilely  under  a  crooked  para- 
phrase." "  These  opinions  (about  the  beginning  of 
the  world,  apparently)  are  to  be  judged  by  those  to 
whom  God  has  committed  the  ordering  of  religion; 
that  is,  to  the  supreme  governors  of  the  Church ;  that 
is,  in  England,  to  the  king."  Charles  II.  apparently 
was  to  decide  whether  the  world  had  a  beginning. 

Putting  aside  for  the  moment  this  quaint  transi- 
tion from  reason  to  the  British  Constitution,  it  is  to 
be  noticed  that  Hobbes  had  expressed  himself  unequi- 
vocally in  the  De  Give  and  the  Leviathan.  By  God,  he 
says,  is  understood  the  cause  of  the  world.  "  To  say 
the  world  is  God,  is  to  say  there  is  no  cause  of  it,  that 
is,  no  God.  ...  To  say  the  world  was  not  created  but 
eternal,  seeing  that  which  is  eternal  has  no  cause,  is 
to  deny  there  is  a  God."  It  is  plain  then  that  if  we 
may  put  these  statements  together,  Hobbes  declares 
that  the  only  proof  of  God's  existence  is  the  creation 
of  the  world,  and  that  we  cannot  possibly  know 


in.]  MAN  151 

whether  the  world  was  or  was  not  created.  In  any 
case,  as  we  have  seen,  Hobbes  always  asserts  most 
emphatically  that  we  really  know  nothing  of  God's 
attributes,  except  his  existence.  Other  attributes  are 
negative  or  metaphorical  or  signs  of  "  honour."  We 
know  nothing  of  God's  "natural  kingdom'  except 
"from  the  principles  of  natural  science,  which  are  so 
far  from  teaching  us  anything  of  God's  nature,  as  they 
cannot  teach  us  our  own  nature  nor  the  nature  of  the 
smallest  creature  living.  And  therefore  when  men 
out  of  the  principles  of  natural  reason  dispute  of  the 
attributes  of  God,  they  but  dishonour  him ;  for  in  the 
attributes  which  we  give  to  God  we  are  not  to  consider 
the  signification  of  philosophical  truth,  but  the  signifi- 
cation of  pious  intention  to  do  him  the  greatest  honour 
we  are  able."  Existence  indeed  implies  something 
more.  Hobbes,  as  we  have  seen,  denies  that  spirits  are 
"  incorporeal "  ;  to  say  that  a  spirit  is  an  "  incorporeal 
substance J:  is  to  say  that  there  is  no  spirit  at  all. 
Bramhall  says  that  the  same  would  apply  to  God. 
Hobbes  replies  that  the  true  question  is  "  whether 
God  be  a  phantasm  (id  est  an  idol  of  the  fancy,  which 
St.  Paul  saith  is  nothing)  or  a  corporeal  spirit,  that  is 
to  say,  something  that  has  magnitude."  He  therefore 
holds  that  God  is  a  "most  pure,  simple,  invisible, 
spirit  corporeal."  He  illustrates  this  by  a  strange 
analogy.  He  has  seen  "  two  waters,  one  of  the  river, 
the  other  a  mineral  water,  so  like  that  no  man  could 
discern  the  one  from  the  other,"  and  yet  when  mixed, 
the  whole  was  indistinguishable  in  appearance  from 
milk.  "If  then  such  gross  bodies  have  so  great 
activity,  what  shall  we  think  of  spirits,  whose  kinds 
be  as  many  as  there  be  kinds  of  liquor,  and  activity 


152  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

greater  ?  "  (How  does  lie  know  that  ?)  "  Can  it 
then  be  doubted  that  God,  who  is  an  infinitely  fine 
spirit  and  withal  intelligent,  can  make  and  change 
all  kinds  of  bodies  as  he  pleaseth  ? ':  God,  then, 
like  other  spirits,  is  corporeal,  though  he  rnay  be 
called  "  incorporeal "  to  imply  that  he  is  "  something 
between  infinitely  subtile  and  nothing:  less  subtile 
than  infinitely  subtile,  and  yet  more  subtile  than  a 
thought."  It  would  be  superfluous  to  examine  this 
singular  hypothesis  to  which  Hobbes  is  driven  by  his 
desire  to  reconcile  his  materialism  with  his  theology. 
It  is  enough  to  remark  that  his  system  would  clearly 
be  more  consistent  and  intelligible  if  he  simply  omitted 
the  theology  altogether. 

Meanwhile  Hobbes  has  another  doctrine  about 
theology  which  is  of  more  interest  and  more  in  accord- 
ance with  his  general  theories.  Religion,  he  says,  is 
peculiar  to  man,  and  its  "  seed "  is  therefore  in  some 
quality  peculiar  to  him.  Such  a  quality  is  his  curios- 
ity as  to  causes  ;  and  though  men  vary,  all  men  are  "  cu- 
rious in  the  search  of  the  causes  of  their  own  good  and 
evil  fortune."  When  he  cannot  discover  true  causes, 
a  man  supposes  such  as  are  suggested  by  his  fancy. 
Meanwhile  his  desire  for  security  puts  him  in  a  state 
of  "  perpetual  solicitude."  He  resembles  Prometheus 
on  the  Caucasus,  "  a  place  of  large  prospect,"  though 
far  from  comfortable.  He  hath  "  his  heart  all  the  day 
long  gnawed  on  by  fear  of  death,  poverty,  or  other 
calamity ;  and  has  no  repose  nor  pause  of  his  anxiety 
but  in  sleep."  The  fear  creates  its  object,  as  it  does 
according  to  his  previous  remark,  in  the  case  of 
dreams.  Men  ignorant  of  causes  have  to  invent  "  some 
power  or  agent  invisible."  It  is  thus  true  that  the 


HI.]  MAN  153 

gods  of  the  Gentiles  "  were  at  first  created  by  human 
fear."  Men  could  not,  again,  make  any  other  guess 
as  to  the  substance  of  these  agents  than  that  it  was 
"  the  same  with  that  of  the  soul  of  man,"  and  that 
the  soul  of  man  was  of  the  same  substance  with  that 
which  appears  in  a  dream  to  sleepers  or  in  a  looking- 
glass  to  men  awake.  These  they  took  for  "  real 
external  substances,"  and  called  them  ghosts,  that 
is  "  thin  aerial  bodies "  —  for  nobody  could  think 
them  really  "  incorporeal."  This  ignorance,  again,  led 
them  to  guess  at  omens  and  prognostics  when  they, 
observed  accidental  coincidences  which  they  took  to 
imply  real  connections.  Naturally  they  guessed  these 
agents  to  resemble  themselves,  and  pacified  them  by 
gifts  and  prayers.  Hobbes  has  already  noted  that 
from  the  difficulty  of  distinguishing  "dreams  and 
other  strong  fancies  from  vision  and  sense  "  arose  the 
old  worship  of  satyrs,  fauns,  nymphs,  and  the  like, 
and  nowadays  the  opinion  that  rude  people  have  of 
fairies,  ghosts,  and  goblins,  and  the  power  of  witches. 
(Witches,  he  has  to  interject,  are  rightly  punished 
because  they  believe  in  their  own  power  of  doing 
mischief,  not  that  "witchcraft  is  any  real  power.") 
Belief  in  fancies  and  ghosts  is  inculcated  to  keep,  in 
credit  the  use  of  exorcism,  of  crosses,  of  holy  water, 
and  other  such  inventions  of  "ghostly  men."  "In 
these  four  things,  opinion  of  ghosts,  ignorance  of 
second  causes,  devotion  towards  what  men  fear,  and 
taking  of  things  casual  for  prognostics,  consisteth 
the  natural  seed  of  religion"  The  seeds  have  been 
cultivated  by  "two  sorts  of  men":  by  founders  of 
commonwealths  and  the  lawgivers  of  the  Gentiles  on 
the  one  hand,  who  "  used  their  own  invention,"  and 


154  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

on  the  other  by  "  Abraham,  Moses,  and  our  blessed 
Saviour/'  who  acted  by  "  God's  commandment  and 
direction."  Both  desired  to  make  men  more  apt  to 
obedience,  laws,  peace,  charity,  and  civil  society ; 
though  in  one  case  religion  was  part  of  "  human 
politics,"  and  in  the  other  of  "divine  politics."  He 
has  then  no  difficulty  in  showing  what  grotesque 
results  followed  from  the  Gentile  religions ;  and  when 
Bramhall  founds  upon  this  passage  a  charge  of 
atheism,  he  can  reply  that  his  account  of  the  origin 
of  religion  tells  against  the  Gentile  superstitions  alone. 
The  savage  people  feared  "  invisible  powers,"  that  is, 
something  which  they  took  to  be  gods ;  so  that  the 
fear  of  a  god,  though  not  the  true  one,  was  to  them 
the  beginning  of  religion,  as  the  fear  of  the  true 
God  was  the  beginning  of  wisdom  to  the  Jews  and 
Christians. 

The  political  aspect  of  his  theory  which  makes 
legislators  the  founders  of  religion  will  be  noticed 
presently.  In  the  Leviathan  he  gives  some  remark- 
able definitions  :  "  Fear  of  power  invisible  feigned 
by  the  mind  or  imagined  from  tales  publicly  allowed 
—  Religion  ;  not  allowed  —  Superstition  ;  and  when 
the  power  imagined  is  truly  such  as  we  imagine  — 
True  Religion."  "  True  religion,"  it  may  be  inferred, 
when  not  publicly  allowed,  is  superstition.  Whether 
Hobbes  wishes  to  draw  that  inference  we  need  not 
decide,  nor  need  we  ask  how  far  he  was  quite  con- 
vinced that  the  history  of  the  Jewish  belief  presents 
so  complete  a  contrast  to  the  history  of  the  religions 
founded  by  other  legislators. 

It  is  enough  to  say  that  Hobbes  is  here  on  the  way 
to  much  later  speculation.  A  hundred  years  afterwards 


in.]  MAN  155 

Hume  in  his  Natural  History  of  Religion  treated  the 
same  topic  with  his  usual  acuteness,  and  suggested 
theories  afterwards  taken  up  by  Comte.  Later 
students  of  the  science  of  religion  have  enormously 
extended  the  range  of  the  inquiry  and  accumulated 
vast  masses  of  evidence  for  various  theories.  In 
Hobbes's  time,  or,  indeed,  in  Hume's  or  even  Comte's, 
it  was  not  possible  to  get  beyond  general  conjectures. 
Hobbes  knew  next  to  nothing  of  the  savage  peoples  to 
whom  he  refers,  and  can  only  guess  as  to  their  probable 
mode  of  thought.  He  is  thinking  chiefly  of  the 
classical  mythologies,  where  he  can  find  plenty  of 
examples  of  grotesque  and  vicious  deities.  All  that 
can  be  said  is  that  he  saw  clearly  the  importance  of 
the  problems  as  to  the  growth  of  religions,  though,  in 
the  absence  of  the  requisite  knowledge,  he  could  only 
make  a  few  very  acute  and  pithy  suggestions. 

If  we  now  come  to  the  question  what  was  Hobbes's 
real  position  in  regard  to  theology,  I  think  that  there 
can  be  only  one  answer.  It  is  quite  clear  that  his, 
like  other  materialistic  systems,  is  incompatible  with 
anything  that  can  be  called  theism.  His  argument 
comes  merely  to  this,  that  if  the  world  was  created  - 
a  point  which,  we  see,  he  admits  to  be  doubtful  —  the 
Creator  must  have  been  a  Being  of  stupendous  power, 
but  one  of  whom  we  are  unable  to  say  anything  else. 
The  doctrine  that  he  is  "  corporeal "  or  an  infinitely 
"  subtile "  matter  occupying  space  is  merely  a  quaint 
attempt  to  evade  the  more  natural  inference  that  he  is 
simply  outside  of  all  knowable  relations.  A  religion 
of  this  kind  is  not  likely  to  give  much  trouble  to 
anybody ;  and  Hobbes's  opponents  were  right  in 
regarding  him  as  virtually  opposed  to  all  possible 


156  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

theology.  What  Hobbes  himself  thought  is  not  quite 
so  obvious.  There  is  a  presumption,  indeed,  that  so 
bold  a  thinker  must  have  seen  the  plain  inferences 
from  his  principles.  If  he  did  not  see  them  for  him- 
self, they  were  pointed  out  by  antagonists  ;  and  though 
Hobbes,  like  most  people,  was  apt  to  think  that 
antagonism  means  misrepresentation,  he  could  scarcely 
fail  to  see  that  they  had  in  his  case  some  ground  for 
their  comments.  His  answers,  indeed,  seem  less  to 
meet  the  arguments  than  to  be  ingenious  devices  for 
shifting  the  question.  Hobbes  certainly  made  his  re- 
serves. When  Spinoza's  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus 
appeared  in  1670  he  said  to  Aubrey  that  Spinoza 
"  has  cut  through  me  a  bar's  length,  for  I  durst  not 
write  so  boldly."  It  would  indeed  be  difficult  to  blame 
a  timid  old  gentleman  for  not  courting  martyrdom. 
The  blame  for  reservation  belongs  to  the  persecutor 
more  than  to  the  persecuted.  It  is,  I  think,  far  more 
remarkable  that  Hobbes  spoke  so  frankly  than  that  he 
did  not  reveal  his  whole  mind.  What  he  actually  did 
was  to  use  language  which,  though  it  caused  general 
antipathy,  and  had  implications  quite  clear  to  the 
qualified  reader,  would  have  been  difficult  to  cite  as 
proofs  of  punishable  opinions  in  a  legal  indictment. 
Every  one  is  agreed  to  admire  the  admirable  candour 
and  love  of  truth  of  Spinoza.  Yet  I  think  that  the 
meaning  attached  by  Spinoza  to  the  word  "  God '  is 
quite  as  unlike  the  ordinary  meaning  of  theologians 
as  the  meaning  attached  to  it  by  Hobbes.  Both  have 
defined  their  meaning  quite  frankly.  If  I  say  that  an 
object  is  white  and  add  openly  that  by  white  I  mean 
what  most  people  call  black,  I  cannot  be  accused  of 
deception,  though  I  may  be  taking  advantage  of  the 


in.]  MAN  157 

verbal  ambiguity  which  more  or  less  binds  the  hands 
of  my  enemies.  It  might  be  pleasanter  to  drop  all 
disguise,  but  I  am  simply  playing  the  game  on  the 
terms  which  they  themselves  have  chosen.  I  do  not, 
indeed,  feel  certain  that  Hobbes  admitted  even  to 
himself  the  true  nature  of  his  position.  He  may  have 
retained  some  of  the  horror  for  "  atheism r  in  which 
he  had  been  educated  and  thrown  dust  in  his  own 
eyes  as  well  as  in  other  people's.  My  chief  reason  for 
doubting  is  that,  as  we  shall  presently  see,  he  relies  in 
his  political  writings  upon  certain  doctrines  as  to 
"  the  laws  of  God,"  which  are  apparently  essential  to 
his  argument,  and  which  could  hardly  be  used  by  one 
to  whom  the  words  meant  nothing.  It  is  true  that 
they  do  not  in  any  case  mean  very  much ;  still  it  is 
possible  that  Hobbes  retained  certain  prepossessions 
which,  as  it  seems  to  me,  were  really  incompatible 
with  his  first  principles. 

3.    Determinism 

I  must  now  speak  of  Hobbes' s  position  in  regard  to 
the  free-will  controversy. 

To  mention  the  topic  is  enough  to  give  the  alarm 
to  all  readers  who  are  not  in  love  with  metaphysical 
hair-splitting  for  its  own  sake.  It  has  become  the 
type  of  fruitless  controversy.  Milton,  in  a  familiar 
passage,  intimated  that  the  argument  was  only  suitable 
to  beings  who  had  an  indefinite  amount  of  time  on 
their  hands  and  to  whom  any  distraction  would  be 
agreeable.  At  times,  indeed,  the  popular  niind  is 
startled  by  some  supposed  consequence  of  "  deter- 
minism." It  is  supposed  to  imply  the  existence  of  a 


158  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Fate  which  forces  people,  whether  they  like  it  or  not, 
to  commit  so  many  murders  in  proportion  to  their 
population,  or  forces  a  sober  person  to  take  to  drink 
because  his  grandfather  was  a  drunkard.  I  am  not 
about  to  argue  the  question,  nor  to  follow  in  detail 
the  brisk  controversy  between  Hobbes  and  Braonhall. 
It  will  be  enough  to  indicate  briefly  the  position  taken 
by  Hobbes  in  regard  to  the  contemporary  phase  of  a 
perennial  discussion.  Milton's  view  was  no  doubt 
natural  in  the  days  of  the  Synod  of  Dort  and  the 
Westminster  Assembly.  The  controversies  between 
Catholics  and  Protestants  necessarily  involved  conflicts 
over  the  free-will  problem.  In  the  Catholic  doctrine 
the  church  is  the  appointed  guardian  of  morality, 
conceived  as  a  system  of  divine  laws.  The  sacraments 
supply  the  means  by  which  men  may  obtain  grace  to 
obey  the  law  and  receive  forgiveness  for  transgressions. 
The  whole  system  supposes  that  men  have  "  free-will '; 
and  acquire  "  merit."  They  can  either  obey  or  dis- 
obey the  law,  and  therefore  they  can  deserve  reward 
or  punishment.  The  Protestant  revolt  against  the 
authority  of  the  Church  led  to  the  assertion  of  prin- 
ciples which  when  logically  developed  struck  at  the 
root  of  the  whole  system.  A  man  can  acquire  no 
"  merit,"  that  is,  no  claim  upon  his  Creator,  for  his 
obedience  to  the  law.  God,  it  must  be  supposed, 
approves  a  man  for  what  he  is,  not  for  what  he  has 
done.  One  man  may  forgive  another  for  an  injury 
when  compensation  has  been  made.  But  the  divine 
forgiveness  can  only  mean  that  the  will  to  do  wrong  is 
destroyed.  Salvation  must  be  gained,  not  by  giving 
satisfaction  for  wrongs,  but  by  the  conformity  of  the 
man's  nature  to  the  divine  order.  The  sinner  must 


in.]  MAN  159 

change  his  heart,  not  balance  his  accounts  with  his 
creditor.  To  the  Protestant,  therefore,  the  vital  point 
became  regeneration  or  conversion,  and  the  sacraments 
have  at  most  a  secondary  importance.  But  it  then 
becomes  difficult  to  admit  "  free-will."  Man  clearly 
cannot  make  himself.  He  cannot  even  contribute  to 
the  work  of  divine  grace ;  for  to  allow  him  a  share  in 
the  process  is  to  admit  some  claim  to  "merit."  Con- 
version, therefore,  must  be  supernatural  and  the  man 
merely  passive. 

While  the  Catholic  divines  were  elaborating  systems 
of  casuistry  and  turning  morality  into  a  code  of  laws 
analogous  to  human  legislation,  the  Protestants  were 
endeavouring  to  form  theories  as  to  the  action  of 
divine  grace  upon  the  human  heart.  They  discussed 
the  "  Five  Articles  "  at  the  Synod  of  Dort,  laid  down 
dogmas  as  to  predestination,  election,  the  atonement, 
the  corruption  of  human  nature  and  its  various  conse- 
quences. The  metaphysical  controversy  was  continued 
with  attempts  to  accept  compromises  with  the  old 
systems,  and  to  find  a  sanction  for  every  dogma  in 
the  Bible,  regarded  as  a  supernatural  act  of  parlia- 
ment, of  which  every  word  was  divinely  inspired.  The 
discussion,  instead  of  tending  to  unity,  seemed  to  be 
only  producing  a  ramification  into  diverging  sects  and 
conflicting  dogmatisms.  It  might  be  shrewdly  sus- 
pected that  the  reasoners  were  getting  out  of  their 
depth,  and  it  was  clear  that  they  were  reaching  some 
shocking  results.  When  free-will  has  disappeared,  it 
seems  hard  that  a  sinner  should  be  tortured  endlessly 
for  doing  what  he  was  predestined  to  do.  But  how 
is  the  difficulty  to  be  met  ?  A  century  later  Jonathan 
Edwards  was  led  by  his  stern  Calvinism  to  write  one 


160  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

of  the  acutest  of  all  treatises  upon  free-will,  and  to 
expound  the  doctrine  of  "  determinism/'  or,  as  it  was 
called,  "  philosophical  necessity."  For  the  present, 
the  discussion  was  mixed  up  with  heterogeneous  ele- 
ments, derived  from  the  traditional  dogmas.  Hobbes, 
though  he  cared  little  for  theological  dogmas,  was 
interested  in  the  metaphysical  part  of  the  controversy. 
He  is  very  little  given  to  quote  authorities ;  but  in  his 
discussion  with  Bramhall,  he  claims  to  be  supported 
on  one  essential  point  by  Luther,  Calvin,  the  Synod 
of  Dort,  and  other  Protestant  authorities.  "All  the 
famous  doctors  of  the  Reformed  Churches,"  he  says, 
"  and  with  them  St.  Augustine,  are  of  the  same  opinion." 
The  problem  was  in  the  air. 

In  England,  Calvinism  was  going  out  of  fashion. 
The  rationalist,  disgusted  by  endless  and  fruitless 
controversy,  hoped  that  unity  might  be  reached  by 
confining  the  creed  to  those  points  (if  any)  upon  which 
all  Christians,  or  perhaps  all  religions,  were  agreed. 
The  metaphysical  subtleties  might  be  left  to  amuse 
professors  in  their  studies.  The  Anglican  divines  had 
accepted  Calvinism  during  the  heat  of  their  contro- 
versy with  Rome.  They  were  now  opposing  Calvinism 
on  one  side  as  much  as  Rome  on  the  other.  "  What 
do  the  Arminians  hold  ?  All  the  best  preferments  in 
England,"  was  the  famous  quibble  which  marked  the 
changed  attitude.  The  Church  of  England,  claiming 
to  be  the  legitimate  continuation  of  the  mediaeval 
church,  inherited  the  old  theories  as  to  the  claims  and 
functions  of  the  priesthood,  which  necessarily  involved 
a  doctrine  of  free-will  and  a  rejection  of  the  Calvinism 
which  had  for  a  time  found  acceptance.  Bramhall  was 
a  man  of  great  vigour,  who  has  been  recently  called  by 


in.]  MAN  161 

a  competent  critic,  "  one  of  the  ablest  champions  ';I  of 
the  Church  of  England.  He  represented  one  special 
antipathy  of  his  opponent.  Hobbes  was  never  tired 
of  denouncing  the  "jargon"  of  the  schoolmen,  and 
regarded  their  doctrines  as  the  great  obstacle  in  the 
way  of  all  intellectual  progress.  At  the  universities, 
however,  the  schoolmen  were  still  held  in  honour  and 
supplied  the  weapons  for  theological  controversy. 
Bramhall  had  sufficient  training  in  the  art  to  wield 
their  writings  with  familiarity  and  no  little  skill  of 
fence.  When  Hobbes  speaks  irreverently  of  these 
authorities,  Bramhall  seems  to  be  as  much  astonished 
as  disgusted.  It  seems  as  if  he  were  quite  unaware 
that  a  revolt  against  the  whole  system  had  long  been 
in  progress.  He  had  obviously  taken  no  interest  in 
the  scientific  movement  represented  by  Bacon  or 
Hobbes.  "  It  troubles  him  to  see  a  scholar  who  hath 
been  long  admitted  into  the  innermost  closet  of  nature 
and  seen  the  hidden  secrets  of  more  subtle  learning, 
so  far  forget  himself  as  to  style  school  learning  no 
better  than  a  plain  jargon,  that  is,  a  senseless  gibberish 
or  a  fustian  language  like  the  chattering  noise  of 
sabots. "  Hobbes,  he  thinks,  objects  to  scholastic  dis- 
tinctions, because  a  sore  eye  is  offended  by  the  sight 
of  the  sun.  Are  all  terms  of  art  to  be  given  up  ?  Is 
the  moral  philosopher  to  "  quit  his  means  and  extremes 
.  .  .,  his  liberty  of  contradiction  and  contrariety  "  ? 
Must  the  "  natural  philosopher  give  over  his  intentional 
species  .  .  .  his  receptive  and  eductive  power  of  the 
matter,  his  qualities  infusce  or  influxce,  symbolce  or  dis- 
symbolce,  his  temperament  ad  pondus  and  ad  justitiam, 
.  .  .  his  sympathies  and  antipathies,  his  antiperi stasis, 
etc.  ?  Are  the  astrologer  and  the  geographer  to  leave 

M 


162  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

their  apogceum  and  perigveum,  their  arctic  and  antarctic 
poles,  their  equator,  zodiac,  zenith,  meridian,  horizon, 
zones,  etc.  ? ':  Hobbes  will  find  that  such  things  are 
necessary  in  every  art.  Let  him  go  on  shipboard  and 
the  mariners  will  not  leave  their  starboard  and  larboard 
because  he  accounts  it  gibberish.  Hobbes  is  quite 
ready  to  part  with  some  of  these  words.  Terms,  he 
thinks,  should  be  thrown  away  when  they  cannot  be 
understood,  and,  when  they  can,  should  be  used  rightly. 
The  astrologer  (unless  the  bishop  means  astronomer1) 
had  better  throw  away  his  whole  trade;  but  to  the 
astronomer  "equator,"  "zodiac,"  and  so  forth,  are  as 
useful  as  saw  or  hatchet  to  a  carpenter.  The  "  meta- 
physician "  should  quit  both  his  terms  and  his  profes- 
sion, and  the  divine  use  only  such  words  as  the  hearer 
can  understand. 

Bramhall  therefore  takes  the  airs  of  a  philosophical 
expert  dealing  with  a  coarse  ignoramus.  He  may  be 
compared  to  a  profound  Hegelian  lecturing  a  disciple 
of  J.  S.  Mill  or  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer.  The  scholastic 
terminology  appears  obscure  to  Hobbes  only  because 
the  subject-matter  is  difficult  and  the  listener  stupid. 
We  do  not  now  despise  each  other  so  heartily  or  express 
our  contempt  so  frankly.  Bramhall  claims  the  victory 
with  a  confidence  which  is  shared  by  his  last  editor, 
who  only  regrets  that  he  should  not  have  met  with  an 
antagonist  "more  worthy  of  him,"  and  should  have 
wasted  time  in  replying  to  "  peevish  and  feeble 
crotchets."  I  fancy  that  Bramhall  is  better  remem- 
bered as  Hobbes's  opponent  than  Hobbes  as  Bramhall's ; 

1  Bramhall  had  some  belief  in  astrology.  "All  judicious 
astronomers  hold  that  the  stars  '  incline '  though  they  do  not 
'necessitate'  the  will." 


in.]  MAN  163 

but  they  represent  modes  of  thought  so  different,  that 
it  is  easy  to  understand  how  each  should  be  triumphant 
in  the  eyes  of  his  own  side. 

Hobbes's  main  purpose  is  obvious.  He  aspires  to 
apply  scientific  methods  to  what  we  now  call  psycho- 
logical and  sociological  problems.  This  leads  him,  like 
many  of  his  successors,  to  deny  altogether  the  possi- 
bility of  "free-will."  Free-will,  as  he  understands  it, 
means  the  presence  of  an  essentially  arbitrary  factor 
in  human  conduct.  If  we  knew  the  whole  character 
of  a  man  and  all  the  motives  that  act  upon  him,  we 
should  still,  if  free-will  be  a  reality,  be  unable  to  predict 
his  action.  Everything  else  being  the  same,  his  choice 
is  indeterminate.  No  one,  of  course,  supposes  his  choice 
to  be  absolutely  arbitrary ;  but,  so  far  as  the  arbitrary 
element  remains,  scientific  certainty  is  impossible. 
Science,  according  to  Hobbes,  means  the  deduction 
of  effects  from  causes.  Free-will  supposes  the  so-called 
chain  to  be  broken.  Given  the  cause,  the  effect  may 
be  this  or  that.  If  this  be  really  implied  in  the  con- 
ception of  free-will,  it  is  obvious  that  if  it  does  not 
destroy  the  possibility,  it  limits  the  field  of  moral 
science.  Hobbes's  whole  doctrine  is  radically  opposed 
to  this  theory.  Man,  he  has  told  us,  is  moved  by 
"  appetites "  and  "  aversions."  On  one  side  these 
appetites  are  literally  "  motions J:  in  the  physical 
organism  :  reactions  set  up  by  contact  with  outside 
things,  following  as  necessarily  as  the  motion  of  the 
hands  of  the  clock  follows  from  the  descent  of  the 
weight.  On  the  other  side  they  appear  to  us  as 
phantasms  —  as  hopes  of  good  and  fears  of  evil ;  good 
being  the  same  as  the  pleasurable,  and  evil  as  the  pain- 
ful. When  we  have  alternating  and  conflicting  hopes 


164  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

and  fears,  we  call  the  process  "  deliberation."  The 
resultant  which  determines  the  action  is  the  last 
appetite,  or,  as  we  call  it,  the  will.  The  "  passions/7 
appetites,  aversions,  hopes,  and  fears  do  not,  he  says, 
proceed  from,  they  are  the  will.  In  his  discussion  with 
Bramhall,  Hobbes  does  not  lay  stress  upon  the  physical 
aspect.  We  know,  he  says,  by  reflecting  on  ourselves, 
that  "deliberation  or  choice'11  means  simply  consider- 
ing the  good  and  evil  consequences  of  our  actions.  Re- 
flection will  also  convince  us  that  nothing  can  begin 
without  a  cause.  Everything  is  caused :  our  actions 
are  caused  by  our  expectations  of  good  and  evil,  or 
(which  is  identical)  of  pleasure  and  pain.  Whether 
we  take  it  physiologically  or  psychologically,  all  con- 
duct is  determined,  or,  as  he  calls  it,  "  necessary." 
Freedom  has  still  a  precise  meaning.  It  means  the 
"absence  of  all  impediments  to  action  that  are  not 
contained  in  the  nature  of  the  agent."  Thus  defined, 
freedom  is  compatible  with  "  necessitation."  I  am  free 
when  my  action  is  necessitated  by  my  own  desires, 
not  by  external  conditions.  I  am  not  free  to  walk  out 
when  the  door  is  locked ;  I  am  free  when  it  is  open. 
But  I  am  "necessitated  to  use  my  freedom  by  the 
desire  which  causes  me  to  walk  out  or  not  to  walk 
out " ;  only  in  this  case  the  necessity  is  in  my  own 
nature,  not  in  the  surroundings.  Freedom,  therefore, 
as  he  constantly  insists,  means  freedom  to  do  what  I 
will ;  but  freedom  to  will  what  I  will  is  nonsense.  A 
man,  in  his  illustration,  may  be  free  to  eat  if  there  is 
no  obstacle  between  him  and  his  food.  But  he  is  not 
free  to  have  or  not  to  have  an  appetite  for  his  food. 
That  is  settled  by  his  organism.  His  will  is  the 
appetite.  The  "  freedom  "  of  the  will,  understood  as 


in.]  MAN  165 

denying  causation,  is  an  illusion.  When  we  do  not 
know  the  causes  of  volition,  we  assume  that  it  is 
uncaused.  Chance  usually  means  our  ignorance. 
Everything,  he  infers,  is  necessary.  He  ought  rather, 
I  think,  to  have  argued  that  "necessary,"  like  "pro- 
bable," "  possible,"  and  so  forth,  really  refers  to  our 
knowledge,  and  means  no  more  than  "  certain." 
His  use  of  the  word  seems  to  imply  that  besides  the 
man  and  his  circumstances,  there  is  an  external  fate 
which  coerces  him. 

So  far,  Hobbes  is  saying  what  has  been  said  by 
later  "  determinists."  Bramhall  calls  him  the  "  ring- 
leader of  a  new  sect,  or  rather  the  first  nominal 
Christian  who  has  raised  from  its  grave  the  '  sleeping 
ghost '  of  the  Stoics'  fate."  Hobbes,  if  Bramhall  is 
correct,  may  be  credited  with  giving  the  purely 
scientific  version  of  the  doctrine  more  or  less  implied 
in  the  Calvinist  theology.  To  Bramhall  it  naturally 
appears  monstrous  and  unintelligible.  He  holds  it  to 
be  as  clear  that  "  there  are  free  actions  which  proceed 
merely  from  election  without  any  outward  necessita- 
tion  "  as  that  there  is  a  sun  in  the  heavens.  That  is 
the  usual  appeal  to  our  consciousness  of  free-will. 
Hobbes,  however,  might  accept  the  phrase,  if  amended, 
by  the  admission  that  there  is  "  inward  necessitation." 
They  agree  that  voluntary  action  implies  "  delibera- 
tion." Hobbes  considers  that  deliberation  is  as  much 
determined  or  necessitated  as  any  other  natural  process. 
Bramhall  replies  by  one  of  the  distinctions  which  to 
Hobbes  were  meaningless  "jargon."  The  "motives'1 
and  "passions,"  he  says,  only  move  the  will  morally; 
they  do  not  determine  it  naturally.  Moral  determina- 
tion, according  to  Hobbes,  is  still  determination.  The 


166  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

will,  says  Bramhall,  hath  a  free  dominion  over  itself; 
she  is  the  mistress  of  human  actions  ;  the  understanding 
is  her  trusty  counsellor  which  she  can  consult  or  not 
as  she  pleases.  Bramhall  talks,  says  Hobbes,  as  if  the 
will  and  the  other  faculties  "  were  men  or  spirits  in 
men's  bellies."  It  is  the  man  and  not  the  will  who 
decides.  In  this  case  Hobbes  hits  the  mark.  Bram- 
hall seems  to  accept  a  kind  of  psychological  mythology 
in  which  abstractions  like  "  the  will  "  are  personified, 
and  logical  distinctions  made  to  imply  different 
faculties  in  the  concrete  individual.  Freedom  no 
doubt  is  a  rational  concept,  for  it  does  not  imply  con- 
tradiction. But  it  does  not  follow  that  because  a 
thing  can  be  rightly  described  by  an  indeterminate 
phrase,  a  concrete  indeterminate  thing  can  exist.  I 
will  not,  however,  go  into  the  argument.  Bramhall,  I 
take  it,  cannot  confute  the  theory  that  conduct  is 
caused,  because  there  are  no  arguments  by  which  it 
can  be  confuted.  It  is  consistent  in  itself.  Whether 
it  can  be  proved  or  whether  it  is  opposed  to  our 
immediate  consciousness  are  other  questions  which  I 
leave  to  those  who  are  amused  by  them.  Neither 
need  I  speak  of  other  arguments,  which  fill  a  large 
space  in  the  dispute,  such  as  the  argument  from  texts : 
whether  the  famous  passage  in  the  Epistle  to  the 
Romans  denies  free-will ;  or  the  question  to  the 
paralytic  person,  "  wilt  thou  be  clean,'7  implies  that  he 
had  free-will.  Nor  will  I  speak  of  the  puzzles  about 
reconciling  the  divine  prescience  to  "indeterminism"  ; 
or  the  difference  between  admitting  that  the  Creator 
permitted  sin,  and  admitting  that  he  caused  it.  The 
arguments  are  familiar,  and  to  Hobbes,  Bramhall 
seems  to  be  constantly  evading  them  by  verbal  dis- 


in.]  MAN  167 

tinctions.  It  is  a  fight  between  a  man  of  science  look- 
ing at  the  facts,  and  a  skilful  dialectician  dodging  them 
under  shelter  of  irrelevant  concepts. 

The  horror  felt  for  determinism  is  due  to  what 
Hobbes  calls  "  certain  inconveniences  "  supposed  to  be 
its  consequences.  For  that  reason  Hobbes  wished,  he 
says,  to  keep  discussion  private.  A  sinner  might 
excuse  himself  —  however  illogically  —  by  saying  that 
his  sin  was  predetermined.  He  did  not  want  a 
murderer  to  say,  "  Mr.  Hobbes  tells  me  that  I  couldn't 
help  it." 

Now  a  rational  theory  of  determinism  may  be,  as  I 
think  that  it  is,  free  from  that  objection.  But  Hobbes's 
version  leads  to  consequences  which  are  startling  to 
the  moralist  and  significant  of  his  general  attitude. 
Bramhall,  as  his  opponents  hold,  confuses  determinism 
with  fatalism.  He  therefore  argues  that  necessity 
makes  laws  unjust,  and  all  advice,  praise,  blame,  books, 
doctors,  and  tutors  absurd.  If  the  future  is  determined 
by  "  unalterable  necessity,  whether  we  be  idle  or 
industrious,  why  do  we  labour  "  ?  The  answer  is  of 
course  obvious.  The  end  is  not  determined  irrespec- 
tively of  the  means.  To  say,  "  If  I  shall  live  till  to- 
morrow, I  shall  live  though  I  run  myself  through  with 
a  sword  to-day,"  is  absurd  ;  for  if  I  am  fated  to  live 
till  to-morrow,  I  am  also  fated  not  to  run  myself 
through  to-day.  It  is  not  absurd  to  make  a  law 
against  crime,  for  the  law  alters  the  conditions,  by 
affecting  the  will.  A  man,  it  may  be,  cannot  refrain 
from  murder  when  there  is  no  law,  but  can  when  he 
knows  he  is  to  be  hanged  for  it.  Murderers,  says 
Hobbes,  are  killed  because  they  are  noxious,  not 
because  they  are  "  not  necessitated."  Hobbes,  that  is, 


168  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

accepts  the  purely  deterrent  theory  of  criminal  law. 
You  are  not  hanged  for  stealing  sheep,  as  the  judge 
said,  but  hanged  in  order  that  sheep  may  not  be 
stolen.  Bramhall,  he  says,  "  takes  punishment  for  a 
kind  of  revenge."  Hobbes,  on  the  other  hand,  denies 
that  any  good  man  will  afflict  another,  except  to  reform 
the  will  of  the  criminal  or  other  men.  "  Nor  can  I 
understand,  having  only  human  ideas,  that  that 
punishment  which  neither  intendeth  the  correction  of 
the  offender  nor  the  correction  of  others  can  proceed 
from  God  ?  '  Hobbes,  I  take  it,  would  in  this  be  ap- 
proved by  all  rational  law  reformers.  Punishment  is 
justifiable  so  far  only  as  it  tends  to  diminish  crime,  and 
not  because  it  gratifies  a  desire  for  vengeance  which 
prompts  the  infliction  of  superfluous  suffering.  Most 
people,  however,  feel  that  his  statement  is  insufficient. 
We  have  a  right  to  destroy  "  all  that  is  noxious,"  saj^s 
Hobbes,  "  both  beasts  and  men."  We  kill  the  murderer 
as  we  kill  the  wolf  ;  and  we  kill  the  wolf  "justly  when 
we  do  it  in  order  to  our  own  preservation."  The 
theory  seems  to  omit  an  essential  element  in  the  case. 
When  we  say  that  punishment  should  be  "just "  do  we 
not  imply  that  there  is  some  essential  difference  between 
killing  a  wolf  and  hanging  a  murderer  ?  But  Hobbes 
is  forced  by  his  logic  to  take  up  one  very  questionable 
position.  Bramhall  asks  him  what,  upon  his  theory,  is 
the  meaning  of  praise  and  blame  ?  If  all  actions  be 
necessary  why  are  they  praiseworthy  or  blameworthy  ? 
We  blame  people,  says  Hobbes,  "because  they  please 
us  not."  Blaming  means  the  saying  that  -a  thing  is 
imperfect.  A  man  is  a  fool  or  a  knave  even  if  he 
cannot  help  it.  When  it  was  said  that  Cato  was 
good  by  nature,  etquia  aliter  esse  nonpotuit,  he  surely 


in.]  MAN  169 

received  very  high  praise.  If  necessity  does  not  make 
praise  meaningless,  why,  asks  Bramhall,  do  we  not 
praise  fire  for  burning  ?  Men  are  the  tennis-balls  of 
destiny,  and  are  good  and  bad  only  as  a  ball  is  good 
or  bad.  Hobbes  replies  that  we  do  blame  fire  or 
poison  as  much  as  we  do  men.  We  do  not  seek  to  be 
revenged  on  them,  "because  we  cannot  make  them  ask 
forgiveness,  as  we  would  make  men  to  do  when  they 
hurt  us."  The  blame  is  the  same  in  both,  "  but  the 
malice  of  man  is  only  against  man." 

When  Hobbes  was  pressed  by  a  reductio  ad  absurdum 
he  generally  had  the  courage  to  swallow  the  absurdity. 
In  this  case  his  logic  had  put  him  in  an  awkward 
place.  Accepting  his  materialism  and  his  thorough- 
going egoism,  two  men  in  opposition  appear  to  us 
simply  as  two  tennis-balls  coming  into  collision.  The 
man,  no  doubt,  might  be  more  consistently  mischievous 
than  the  ball,  as  he  is  supposed  to  be  malicious.  The 
ball  might  sometimes  give  an  impulse  in  the  right 
direction,  while  the  wicked  man  will  always  aim  at 
doing  injury.  Still  so  long  as  a  man  considers  his  own 
feelings  exclusively,  the  difference  between  blaming  a 
poison  and  blaming  the  poisoner  seems  to  be  one  of 
degree  rather  than  of  kind.  The  determinist  may  hold 
that  Hobbes's  error  lay  not  in  assuming  that  human 
motives  act  regularly,  but  in  failing  to  take  into 
account  the  man  behind  the  thing,  and  those  emotions 
of  love  and  hatred  which  imply  sympathy  and  a  direct 
interest  in  the  happiness  or  sorrow  of  others.  The 
difficulty  comes  out  when  he  is  arguing  the  question  of 
divine  justice.  Of  God,  according  to  Hobbes,  we  really 
know  nothing,  except  that  he  is  omnipotent.  It  is, 
then,  only  from  that  attribute  that  we  can  derive  his 


170  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

justice.  Beasts  are  subject  to  death  and  torment ;  yet 
"  they  cannot  sin."  It  was  God's  will  it  should  be  so. 
"  Power  irresistible  justifieth  all  actions,  really  and  pro- 
perly, in  whomsoever  it  be  found."  It  is,  he  adds,  to 
be  found  in  God  only.  "  God  cannot  sin  because  his 
doing  a  thing  makes  it  just  and  consequently  no  sin ; 
and  because  whatsoever  can  sin  is  subject  to  another's 
law,  which  God  is  not ;  and  therefore  it  is  blasphemy 
to  say  God  can  sin."  Hobbes,  it  would  seem,  would 
have  been  more  consistent  if  he  had  left  out  "justice ': 
altogether.  His  God  —  the  creator  of  the  physical 
universe  —  is  the  author  of  what  the  man  of  science 
calls  "the  laws  of  nature."  But  they  are  simply  the 
mechanical  laws.  It  is  not "  just "  that  weights  should 
balance  each  other  when  they  are  proportioned  in  a 
certain  way  to  the  length  of  the  arms  of  a  lever  ;  it  is 
simply  a  fact.  Morality  has  nothing  to  do  one  way 
or  the  other  with  the  motions  of  the  planets  or  the 
"laws  of  gravitation."  The  physical  system  of  the 
universe  is  morally  neutral.  Morality  can  only  begin 
with  the  conscious  and  sentient  being.  The  assump- 
tion, however,  that  a  "law  of  nature"  means  the  same 
in  both  cases  becomes  very  important  in  Hobbes's 
theory  of  the  State,  where  we  shall  meet  it  again. 

Meanwhile  it  may  be  remarked  for  the  old  gentle- 
man's credit  that  he  is  shocked  by  one  inference  drawn 
by  others.  Bramhall  has  argued  from  "  eternal  tor- 
ments "  :  their  existence  proves  liberty.  "  To  take  away 
liberty  hazards  heaven  but  undoubtedly  it  leaves  no 
hell."  Some  people  might  consider  that  consequence 
to  be  a  partial  compensation.  Bramhall,  however,  has 
no  doubt  about  hell ;  and  the  Calvinists,  though  they 
took  away  liberty,  were  quite  convinced  that  the 


in.]  MAN  171 

eternal  torment  of  sinners  was  just.  Hobbes  was  so 
far  with  them  that  he  was  bound  to  admit  the  justice 
of  any  actually  existing  arrangement,  but  he  refuses 
to  admit  the  existence  of  hell.  Though  God  may 
"afflict  a  man,  and  not  for  sin,  without  injustice,  shall 
we  think  him  so  cruel  as  to  afflict  a  man,  and  not  for 
sin,  with  extreme  and  endless  torment  ?  Is  it  not 
cruelty  ?  No  more  than  to  do  the  same  for  sin,  when 
he  that  so  doeth  might  without  trouble  have  kept  him 
from  sinning."  He  asks,  however,  where  the  Scrip- 
tures say  that  "  a  second  death  is  an  endless  life  ?  Or 
do  the  doctors  say  it  ?  Then  perhaps  they  do  but  say 
so  and  for  reasons  best  known  to  themselves."  "  It 
seemeth  hard  to  say,"  he  observes  elsewhere,  "  that 
God,  who  is  the  father  of  mercies,  that  doth  in  heaven 
and  earth  all  that  he  will,  that  hath  the  hearts  of  all 
men  in  his  disposing,  that  worketh  in  men  both  to  do 
and  to  will  .  .  .  should  punish  men's  transgressions 
without  any  end  of  time  and  with  all  the  extremity  of 
torture  that  men  can  imagine  and  more."  Hobbes 
managed  to  reconcile  his  theory  to  the  orthodox  view 
in  a  rather  singular  fashion.  But  modern  divines 
will  not  quarrel  with  him  for  declining  to  believe  in 
the  old  doctrine  of  damnation. 

One  other  remark  must  be  added.  Hobbes  is  not 
content  with  resolving  the  divine  justice  into  power. 
Human  justice  is  equally  the  creature  of  power. 
Natural  goodness  differs,  he  says,  from  moral.  A 
horse  has  natural  goodness  if  he  is  strong  and  gentle 
and  so  forth ;  and  if  there  were  no  laws,  there  would 
be  as  much  "  moral  good"  in  a  horse  as  in  a  man.  It 
is  the  law  which  makes  the  difference.  Law-makers 
may  err ;  but  from  obedience  to  the  law,  whether 


172  HOBBES  [CHAP.  in. 

made  in  error  or  not,  proceeds  "  moral  praise."  Since 
oar  notions  of  good  and  bad  are  relative  and  mean 
simply  what  pleases  or  displeases  us,  we  can  only  get  a 
common  rule  by  subjection  to  the  law.  "  All  the  real 
good,  which  we  call  honest  and  morally  virtuous,  is 
that  which  is  not  repugnant  to  the  law,  civil  or  natural ; 
for  the  law  is  all  the  right  reason  we  have,  and  ...  is 
the  infallible  rule  of  moral  goodness.''  Our  fallibility 
compels  us  to  "  set  up  a  sovereign  governor "  and 
agree  that  his  law  shall  be  to  us  in  the  place  of  right 
reason.  He  illustrates  this  principle  from  card- 
playing.  When  men  have  turned  up  trumps,  "  their 
morality  consisteth  in  not  renouncing,"  that  is,  in 
observing  the  rules  of  the  game ;  and  so  "  in  civil 
conversation  our  morality  is  all  contained  in  not  dis- 
obeying of  the  laws." 

This  doctrine  —  not  at  first  sight  very  satisfactory  — 
will  be  more  intelligible  when  we  have  considered  the 
Leviathan. 


CHAPTER  IV 

THE    STATE1 

1.    Contemporary  Controversies 

WE  come  now  to  the  third  part  of  Hobbes's  philo- 
sophy. He  is  to  base  a  science  of  politics  upon  the 
doctrines  already  expounded.  We  become  aware  that 
there  is  a  certain  breach  of  continuity.  To  understand 
his  line  of  thought,  it  is  necessary  to  take  note  both 
of  the  problems  in  which  he  was  specially  interested, 
and  the  form  into  which  the  arguments  had  been 
moulded  by  previous  thinkers.  He  applies  to  the 
questions  of  the  day  certain  conceptions  already 
current  in  political  theory,  though  he  uses  them  in 
such  a  way  as  materially  to  alter  their  significance. 

Hobbes's  theory  in  the  first  place  involves  the 
acceptance  of  a  so-called  "  Law  of  Nature."  "  Nature," 
as  we  know,  is  a  word  contrived  in  order  to  introduce 
as  many  equivocations  as  possible  into  all  the  theories, 
political,  legal,  artistic,  or  literary,  into  which  it  enters. 

1  Hobbes's  political  theory  is  given  in  three  books  :  the 
De  Corpore  Politico,  which  was  the  second  part  of  his  first 
treatise,  and  is  reprinted  in  the  fourth  volume  of  the  English 
works  ;  the  De  Give,  which  is  in  the  Latin  works,  vol.  iii., 
and  an  English  translation  of  which,  by  Hobbes  himself,  forms 
the  second  volume  of  the  English  works  ;  and  the  Leviathan, 
which  forms  the  third  volume  of  the  English  works. 

173 


174  HOBBES  [CHAP, 

The  "  Law  of  Nature,"  as  writers  upon  jurisprudence 
tell  us,  was  invented  by  Eoman  lawyers  with  the  help 
of  Stoic  philosophers.  The  lawyers,  having  to  deal 
with  the  legal  systems  of  the  numerous  races  which 
came  into  contact  with  Rome,  were  led  to  recognise  a 
certain  body  of  laws  common  to  all.  Such  law  came 
to  be  considered  as  laid  down  by  Nature.  It  was  a 
product  of  the  human  nature  common  to  Greeks  and 
Komans,  and  not  affected  by  the  special  modifications 
by  which  Romans  are  distinguished  from  Greeks.  It 
belonged  to  the  genus  man,  not  to  the  species  nation. 
The  philosopher,  meanwhile,  took  the  Law  of  Nature 
to  be  law  imposed  by  the  divine  author  of  nature,  dis- 
coverable by  right  reason,  and  therefore  common  to 
all  reasoning  beings.  The  law  in  either  case  is 
"  natural  "  because  universally  valid.  But  this  may 
cover  two  diverging  conceptions.  To  the  man  of 
science  "  nature  "  means  everything  actually  existing. 
One  quality  cannot  be  more  "  natural "  than  another, 
though  it  may  be  more  widely  diffused.  A  scientific 
investigator  of  jurisprudence  would  inquire  what  sys- 
tems of  law  prevail  in  different  countries,  and  would 
seek  to  discover  the  causes  of  uniformity  or  difference. 
The  inquirer  is  so  far  simply  concerned  with  the  ques- 
tion of  fact,  and  to  him  the  exceptional  is  just  as  much 
a  natural  product  as  the  normal  legislation.  The 
scientific  point  of  view  is  that  from  which  one  might 
expect  Hobbes  to  treat  the  question.  He  accepts, 
however,  the  Law  of  Nature  in  another  sense. 
It  meant  an  ideal,  not  an  actual  law,  and  tells 
us  what  ought  to  be,  not  what  is.  There  may  of 
course  be  a  presumption  that  a  law  (if  there  is  such 
law)  which  is  universally  accepted  is  also  dictated  by 


iv.]  THE   STATE  175 

reason ;  or  a  state  may  be  so  happily  constituted  that 
the  perception  that  a  law  is  reasonable  may  involve 
its  acceptance  in  the  actual  system.  But  in  any  case 
the  Law  of  Nature  is  supposed  to  be  the  type  to  which 
the  actual  law  should  be  made  to  conform,  and  there- 
fore implies  a  contrast  and  occasional  conflict  between 
the  two  systems. 

Hobbes's  view  implies  another  distinction.  Every 
one  admits  that  laws  may  rightly  vary  according 
to  circumstances  within  certain  limits.  There  are 
laws,  we  may  say,  which  it  is  right  to  obey  because 
they  are  the  law,  and  others  which  are  the  law  because 
it  is  right  to  obey  them.  In  England  the  law  of  the 
road  tells  carriages  to  keep  to  the  left,  and  in  France 
to  keep  to  the  right.  We  clearly  ought  to  obey  each 
rule  in  its  own  country.  But  there  are  other  cases. 
In  some  countries  the  law  permits  or  enforces  rules  of 
marriage  which  in  other  countries  are  held  to  be 
immoral  and  revolting.  Is  it  true  in  this  case  also 
that  each  law  is  right  in  its  own  country,  or  is  one  set 
of  laws  to  be  condemned  as  contrary  to  the  Law  of 
Nature  ?  Given  the  Law  of  Nature,  that  is,  how  are 
we  to  decide  what  sphere  of  discretion  is  to  be  left  to 
the  legislator  ?  Can  he  deal  with  the  most  vital  as  well 
as  the  most  trivial  relations,  or  how  is  his  proper  sphere 
of  authority  to  be  denned  ?  Where  does  "  positive  ' 
law  begin  and  natural  law  end  ?  This  involves  the 
problem,  how  far  does  the  power  of  the  legislature 
extend,  or  what  is  the  relation  between  the  sovereign 
and  the  subject.  That  was  a  problem  which  had  not 
been  discussed  in  the  classical  philosophy.  Man  as  a 
"  political  animal ';  was  so  identified  with  the  State 
that  citizenship  was  an  essential  part  of  him.  Different 


176  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

forms  of  government  might  be  compared,  but  the 
individual  could  not  be  conceived  as  existing  indepen- 
dently of  the  State.  To  Hobbes  the  State  had  become 
an  "  artificial "  construction,  and  therefore  its  relation 
to  the  units  of  which  it  was  constructed  had  to  be 
settled  and  was  vitally  important. 

The  theory  of  sovereignty  had  become  interesting 
when  there  were  rival  claimants  to  sovereignty.  The 
Christian  Church,  beginning  as  a  voluntary  association 
outside  the  State,  and  appealing  to  men  in  their 
individual  capacity,  had  become  a  gigantic  organisation 
with  an  elaborate  constitution  and  legal  system.  It 
had  come  into  collision,  alliance,  and  rivalry  with  the 
empire.  According  to  the  accepted  theory,  both 
powers  had  legitimate  claims  to  allegiance.  Pope  and 
emperor  were  compared  to  the  sun  and  moon,  though 
it  might  be  disputed  which  was  the  sun  and  which  was 
the  moon,  or  whether  they  were  not  rather  two  inde- 
pendent luminaries.  In  the  great  controversies  which 
arose,  the  Church  had  an  obvious  advantage.  It 
derived  its  authority  from  direct  revelation.  It 
represented  on  earth  the  supreme  Being,  and  was 
entrusted  by  him  with  power  to  enforce  the  moral  laws 
which  coincide  with  the  Law  of  Nature.  As  the  empire 
could  claim  no  special  revelation,  the  advocates  of  its 
claims  had  to  find  some  independent  support  for  them 
in  the  Law  of  Nature.  To  the  question,  then,  whence 
is  derived  the  obligation  to  obey  the  State,  or  rather 
the  ruler,  there  was  but  one  obvious  answer.  "  All 
obligation,"  says  Hobbes,  "  derives  from  contract." 
It  is  part  of  the  Law  of  Nature  that  man  should 
observe  compacts.  If  therefore  the  relation  between 
sovereign  and  subject  depends  upon  a  compact,  there 


iv.]  THE   STATE  177 

is  a  sufficient  obligation  to  obedience  though  the  ruler 
has  not  a  special  commission  from  God.  It  could 
not,  it  is  true,  be  proved  that  such  a  compact  had 
ever  been  made,  nor  that,  if  made  in  one  generation, 
it  would  be  binding  on  the  next,  nor  was  it  possible  to 
say  what  were  the  exact  terms  of  the  supposed  com- 
pact. But  such  cavils  were  trifles.  They  could  be 
met  by  saying  that  there  was  an  "  implicit "  contract, 
and  that  it,  no  doubt,  prescribed  reasonable  terms. 
This  theory  was  gradually  developed  in  the  middle 
ages,  and  when  Hobbes  was  a  young  man  it  had 
acquired  especial  currency  from  the  great  book  in 
which  Grotius  had  adopted  it,  when  applying  the  Law 
of  Nature  to  regulate  the  ethics  of  peace  and  war.1 

This  set  of  conceptions  gives  Hobbes's  starting- 
point,  though  in  his  hands  the  Law  of  Nature  and  the 
social  compact  received  a  peculiar  development,  or, 
indeed,  seemed  to  be  turned  inside  out.  He  applied 
them  to  the  great  controversies  in  which  he  and  his 
contemporaries  were  specially  interested.  The  com- 
plicated struggles  of  the  Reformation  period  had 
raised  issues  which  were  still  undecided.  Church  and 
State,  whatever  the  theory  of  their  relations,  were  so 
closely  connected  as  to  form  parts  of  one  organism, 
and  a  separation  of  them,  such  as  is  contemplated 
by  modern  speculation,  was  unthinkable.  If  the  two 
bodies  had  conflicting  claims,  they  were  also  recipro- 

1  A  very  remarkable  book,  the  Politics  of  Johannes  Althusius 
(1557-1636),  that  appeared  in  1603,  anticipated  much  that  Hobbes 
afterwards  said,  and  played  a  considerable  part  in  the  evolu- 
tion of  the  theory  of  "  Naturrecht."  Professor  Gierke's  most 
learned  and  interesting  book  upon  Althusius  gives  a  full 
account  of  his  doctrine  and  of  his  relation  to  Hobbes  among 
many  others. 

N 


178  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

cally  necessary.  Their  systems  of  legislation  were  not 
independent,  but  interpenetrating.  Each  implied  the 
other,  and  the  State  was  bound  to  suppress  heresy,  as 
the  Church  to  condemn  rebellion.  The  disruption  of 
the  old  system  implied  both  civil  and  foreign  war. 
The  lines  of  cleavage  ran  through  both  Church  and 
State,  and  in  each  fragment  the  ecclesiastical  and 
secular  system  had  to  readjust  their  relations.  When 
in  England  Henry  VIII.  renounced  the  authority  of 
the  pope,  he  had  to  become  a  bit  of  a  pope  himself. 
In  Scotland  the  Church,  though  it  might  suppose  that 
it  had  returned  to  primitive  purity,  could  not  be 
expected  for  that  reason  to  relinquish  its  claims  to 
authority  over  the  laity.  In  the  famous  "  Monarcho- 
machist"  controversy,  Jesuits  agreed  with  Scottish 
Protestants  and  French  Huguenots  in  defending 
tyrannicide.  They  had  a  common  interest  in  limiting 
the  claims  of  the  secular  power.  Jacques  Clement 
and  Ravaillac  gave  a  pointed  application  in  France  to 
the  Jesuit  doctrine ;  and  the  Scots  had  to  make  a 
case  against  Queen  Mary.  Meanwhile  the  claims  of 
the  Catholic  Church  were  the  cause  or  the  pretext  of 
the  warfare  which  culminated  in  the  Spanish  Armada. 
The  patriotic  Englishman  regarded  the  pope  as  the 
instigator  or  accomplice  of  the  assailants  of  our  national 
independence.  Persecution  of  priests  seemed  to  be 
necessary,  even  if  cruel,  when  priests  were  agents  of 
the  power  which  supported  hostile  fleets  and  inspired 
murderous  conspiracies.  Throughout  the  seventeenth 
century  the  protestant  Englishman  suffered  from 
"  papacy  "  on  the  brain,  and  his  fear  flashed  into  panic 
for  the  last  time  when  Hobbes  was  dying.  During  his 
youth  the  keenest  controversy  had  been  raging  over 


iv.]  THE   STATE  179 

the  claims  of  the  papacy.  Jarnes  I.  himself  and  his 
most  learned  divines,  such  as  Andrewes  and  Donne, 
were  arguing  against  the  great  Catholic  divines, 
Suarez  and  Bellarmine.  The  controversy  turned 
especially  upon  the  imposition  of  the  oath  renouncing 
the  doctrine  of  the  right  of  the  pope  to  depose  kings. 
To  that  right  was  opposed  the  "divine  right  of 
kings  " :  thereby  being  meant,  not  that  kings  had  a 
"  right  divine  to  govern  wrong,"  but  that  the  king's 
right  was  as  directly  derived  from  Heaven  as  the  rights 
of  the  Church. 

Hobbes,  as  we  shall  see,  was  deeply  impressed  by 
these  problems.  The  power  of  the  Catholic  Church  to 
enforce  its  old  claims  was  rapidly  disappearing;  but 
men  are  often  most  interested  in  discussing  the  means 
of  escaping  the  dangers  of  the  day  before  yesterday. 
While  Hobbes  was  elaborating  his  system,  great  polit- 
ical issues  seemed  to  turn  upon  the  relation  between 
the  spiritual  and  secular  authority.  Meanwhile  the 
purely  political  were  inextricably  mixed  up  with 
ecclesiastical  questions.  James's  formula,  "  no  bishop, 
no  king,"  expressed  the  fact.  The  Church  of  England 
was  in  the  closest  alliance  with  the  royal  authority  ; 
"passive  obedience 7;  to  the  king  became  almost  an 
essential  doctrine,  even  with  liberal  Anglican  divines ; 
and  the  rebellion  was  the  outcome  of  the  discontent  in 
both  spheres.  In  England  the  claim  of  parliament  to 
a  share  of  power  came  first,  but  the  power  was  to  be 
applied  on  behalf  of  religious  Puritanism.  In  Scotland 
the  Church  question  was  most  prominent ;  but  the 
Church,  in  the  rule  of  which,  as  James  complained, 
Tom,  Dick,  and  Harry  had  claimed  to  have  a  voice, 
also  represented  the  aspirations  of  the  nation.  The 


180  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

political  problem  was  equally  important,  whatever 
might  be  the  motives  for  demanding  political  power. 
The  question  in  England  was  whether  the  ancient 
parliamentary  institutions  were  to  be  preserved  and 
developed,  or  to  be  allowed  to  fall  into  decay  as  in 
other  European  countries  where  the  State  was  being 
organised  on  different  lines.  In  later  days,  writers, 
who  held  the  British  Constitution  to  be  an  embodi- 
ment of  perfect  wisdom,  naturally  venerated  the 
Hampdens  and  Eliots  as  representatives  of  the  ulti- 
mately victorious,  and  therefore  rightful  cause. 

As  Hobbes  altogether  condemned  their  principles, 
we  must  remind  ourselves  how  things  appeared  at 
the  time.  To  men  who  desired  a  vigorous  national 
government  —  which  is  surely  a  very  reasonable  desire 
—  the  claims  of  the  parliamentary  party  appeared  to 
be  a  hopeless  obstacle.  All  men  admitted  that  the 
king  was  to  have  the  fullest  authority  over  the 
national  policy ;  he  might  make  war  or  peace  without 
consulting  anybody ;  and  if  he  could  make  it  at  his 
own  expense,  parliament  had  no  ground  for  inter- 
ference. The  only  thing  which  it  could  do  was  to 
refuse  money  if  he  wanted  it  for  a  policy  which  it 
disliked.  It  was  as  if  the  crew  of  a  ship  of  war  gave 
the  command  unreservedly  to  the  captain,  but,  if 
they  disliked  the  direction  in  which  he  was  steering, 
showed  disapproval  by  turning  off  the  steam.  That 
obviously  would  be  a  clumsy  method.  Parliament  did 
not  superintend  or  give  general  directions,  but  could 
throw  the  whole  system  out  of  gear  when  it  pleased. 
We  know,  of  course,  how  the  struggle  resulted  in  the 
supremacy  of  parliament,  and  of  that  party  organisa- 
tion which  enabled  it  to  act  as  a  unit,  and  to  regulate 


iv.]  THE    STATE  181 

the  whole  national  policy  with  a  certain  continuity  of 
purpose.  In  Hobbes's  time  not  only  could  such  a 
system,  as  historians  agree,  occur  to  no  one,  but  if  it 
had  occurred  it  would  have  been  impracticable.  To 
be  efficient  it  required,  not  merely  an  exposition  of 
principles,  but  the  development  of  a  mutual  under- 
standing between  the  different  classes,  which  was  not 
less  essential  because  not  expressed  in  any  legal  docu- 
ment. The  art  of  parliamentary  government  has  to 
be  learnt  by  practice. 

Another  remark  is  now  pretty  obvious.  The  British 
people  managed  to  work  out  a  system  which  had,  as 
we  all  believe,  very  great  advantages  and  may  justify 
some  of  the  old  panegyrics.  Men  could  speak  more 
freely  —  if  not  always  more  wisely  —  in  England  than 
elsewhere,  and  individual  energy  developed  with  many 
most  admirable,  if  with  some  not  quite  admirable  con- 
sequences. But  the  success  was  won  at  a  cost.  The 
central  authority  of  the  State  was  paralysed ;  and 
many  observers  may  admit  that  in  securing  liberty  at 
the  price  of  general  clumsiness  and  inefficiency  of  all 
the  central  administrative  functions,  the  cost  has  been 
considerable.  It  is  desirable  to  remember  this  point 
when  we  come  to  Hobbes's  special  theories.  To  him 
the  demands  of  the  parliamentary  party  appeared  to 
imply  a  hopeless  disorganization  of  the  political 
machinery.  His  political  writings,  though  professing 
to  be  a  piece  of  abstract  logic,  are  also  essentially 
aimed  at  answering  these  questions.  The  vital  pro- 
blem involved  was,  as  he  thought,  what  is  sovereignty 
and  who  should  be  sovereign  ?  The  State,  on  one 
side,  was  struggling  with  the  Church — whether  the 
Church  of  Rome  or  the  Church  of  Scotland,  —  and,  on 


182  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

the  other  hand,  the  supreme  power  was  claimed  for 
king  alone,  for  parliament  alone,  and  for  some  com- 
bination of  the  two.  What  will  a  scientific  analysis 
enable  us  to  say  as  to  the  general  nature  of  the 
supreme  power  and  as  to  the  best  constitution  of  a 
body  politic.  The  country,  as  he  says,  for  some  years 
before  the  civil  war,  "  was  boiling  over  with  questions 
concerning  the  rights  of  dominion  and  the  obedience 
due  from  subjects  "  :  a  state  of  things  which  "  ripened 
and  plucked "  from  him  the  third  part  of  his  philo- 
sophy before  the  other  parts  were  ready. 

2.    The  Social  Contract 

Hobbes's  political  theories  are  expounded  in  the 
De  Corpore  Politico  (the  little  treatise  of  1640),  the  De 
Give,  and  the  Leviathan.  The  title  of  the  last  of  these 
works  is  suggested  by  certain  words  in  the  Book  of 
Job :  "  Non  est potestas  super  terram  quce  comparetur  ei." 
They  are  printed  at  the  head  of  the  quaint  allegorical 
title-page,  where  a  composite  giant,  his  body  made  of 
human  beings,  holds  the  sword  in  one  and  a  crosier  in 
the  other  hand,  while  beneath  him  is  a  wide  country 
with  a  town,  a  fort,  and  a  church  in  the  foreground,  and 
below  it  are  various  symbols  of  temporal  and  spiritual 
power.  The  great  Leviathan,  he  tells  us,  is  that 
mortal  god  to  which  we  owe,  under  the  immortal  God, 
our  peace  and  defence.  But  he  is  also  a  machine.  We 
are  to  take  him  to  pieces  in  imagination,  as  we  actually 
take  to  pieces  a  watch  to  understand  its  construc- 
tion. -  We  have  already  seen  the  statement  of  Hobbes's 
method.  It  is  impossible  to  deduce  the  properties  of 
this  complex  mechanism  by  the  synthetical  method ; 


iv.]  THE   STATE  183 

but  by  analysing  the  observed  "  motions  of  the  mind  " 
we  can  discover  its  essential  principles.  Justice,  he 
says,  means  giving  to  each  man  his  own.  How  does  a 
man  <^ie  to  have  an  "  own  "  ?  Because  community  of 
goods  breeds  contention,  while  reason  prescribes  peace. 
From  the  regulation  of  the  "  concupiscible  "  nature  by 
the  "  rational "  arises  the  system  of  moral  and  civil 
laws  embodied  in  the  great  Leviathan.  We  have  to 
examine  this  process  in  detail.  Men  have,  as  we  have 
seen,  "  a  perpetual  and  restless  desire  of  power  after 
power.'7  In  the  next  place,  men  are  naturally  equal. 
The  weakest  in  body,  at  any  rate,  may  kill  the 
strongest,  and  there  is  a  still  greater  equality  in  mind. 
This  doctrine  of  natural  equality  he  tries  to  establish 
by  rather  quaint  arguments.  "  Every  man,"  he  says, 
"  thinks  himself  as  wise,  though  not  as  witty  or  learned 
as  his  neighbours.  What  better  proof  can  there  be  of 
equality  of  distribution  than  that  every  man  is  con- 
tented with  his  share  ?"  That  is  hardly  convincing; 
but  what  Hobbes  means  to  say  is  that  no  man  has 
such  a  superiority  over  his  fellows  as  would  make  him 
secure  in  the  chaotic  struggle  of  "  the  state  of  nature." 
When  two  men  want  the  same  thing,  therefore,  each 
will  have  a  chance.  Competition,  diffidence  (a  distrust 
of  each  other),  and  glory  (the  desire,  we  may  say,  for 
prestige)  are  the  three  principal  causes  of  quarrel. 
"  The  first  maketh  men  invade  for  gain ;  the  second 
for  safety ;  the  third  for  reputation."  When  there  is 
no  common  power  to  overawe,  there  will  be  a  "  war  of 
every  man  against  every  man."  War,  he  explains,  is 
not  confined  to  actual  fighting,  but  exists  where  there 
is  a  "  known  disposition  thereto ':  and  "  no  assur- 
ance to  the  contrary."  So  long  as  this  state 


184  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

continues,  "there  is  no  place  for  industry,  because  the 
fruit  thereof  is  uncertain,"  and  (besides  many  other 
wants)  "  no  arts,  no  letters,  no  society,  and  which  is 
worst  of  all,  continual  fear  and  danger  of^polent 
death ;  and  the  life  of  man  solitary,  poor,  -  nasty, 
brutish,  and  short."  Do  you  object  to  this  account  of 
man  ?  Look  at  experience.  Does  not  a  man  arm 
himself  when  he  is  going  a  journey?  Does  he  not 
lock  the  chests  in  his  own  house,  although  he  knows 
that  there  are  public  officers  to  protect  them  ?  What 
opinion  does  that  imply  of  his  fellow  subjects  or  of 
his  servants  ?  "  Does  he  not  as  much  accuse  mankind 
by  his  actions,  as  I  do  by  my  words  ? ' 

Bat  was  there  ever  such  a  "  state  of  nature  "  ?  Not 
perhaps  over  the  whole  world,  though  in  America 
many  savages  live  in  this  nasty  and  brutish  fashion. 
If,  however,  that  were  not  so  with  particular  men, 
"  yet  in  all  times  kings  and  persons  of  sovereign  autho- 
rity, because  of  their  independency,  are  in  continual 
jealousies,  and  in  the  state  and  posture  of  gladiators ; 
having  their  weapons  pointing  and  their  eyes  fixed  on 
one  another  -  -  that  is  their  forts,  garrisons,  and  guns 
upon  the  frontiers  of  their  kingdoms  —  and  continual 
spies  upon  their  neighbours.57  The  argument  is 
certainly  not  obsolete,  nor  the  remark  which  follows. 
"  Because  they  uphold  thereby  the  industry  of  their 
subjects,  there  does  not  follow  from  it  that  misery 
which  accompanies  the  liberty  of  particular  men." 
Now  where  every  man  is  at  war  with  every  man,  "  the 
notions  of  right  and  wrong,  justice  and  injustice,  have 
no  place.  Where  there  is  no  common  power  there  is 
no  law  ;  where  no  law,  no  injustice.  Force  and  fraud 
are  in  war  the  two  cardinal  virtues."  Justice  and 


iv.]  THE   STATE  185 

injustice  "relate  to  men  in  society,  not  in  solitude." 
In  such  a  state  of  things,  there  can  be  "  no  mine  and 
thine  distinct,  but  only  that  to  be  every  man's  that  he 
can  get  and  for  so  long  as  he  can  keep  it." 

"...  the  good  old  rule 
Sufficeth  them,  the  simple  plan, 
That  they  should  take  who  have  the  power, 

And  they  should  keep  who  can," 

as  Wordsworth  puts  it.  This  is  the  "  ill  condition  " 
in  which  man  is  placed  "  by  mere  nature."  There  is  a 
possibility  of  his  getting  out  of  it,  partly  because  some 
passions,  fear  of  death,  desire  of  comfort,  and  hope  of 
securing  it  induce  men  to  peace,  and  partly  because 
"  reason  suggesteth  convenient  articles  of  peace." 

This  is  Hobbes's  famous  theory  that  the  "state  of 
nature  "  is  a  state  of  war.  It  does  not  imply,  he  says, 
that  men  are  "  evil  by  nature."  The  desires  are  not 
themselves  wicked,  though  at  times  they  may  cause 
wicked  actions.  "  Children  grow  peevish  and  do  hurt 
if  you  do  not  give  them  all  they  ask  for  ;  but  they  do 
not  become  wicked  till,  being  capable  of  reason,  they 
continue  to  do  hurt."  A  wicked  man  is  a  child  grown 
strong  and  sturdy ;  and  malice  is  a  defect  of  reason  at 
the  age  when  reasonable  conduct  is  to  be  expected. 
Nature  provides  the  faculties  but  not  the  education. 
The  doctrine  should  be  tested  by  its  truth,  not  by  its 
pleasantness.  Hobbes  accepts  in  part  the  method  of 
Machiavelli,  who  clearly  announced  that  he  was  con- 
cerned with  what  actually  happened,  not  with  what 
ought  to  happen.  To  adopt  that  plan  is  to  undertake 
to  tell  unpleasant  truths,  and  to  tell  unpleasant  truths 
is,  according  to  most  readers,  to  be  "  cynical."  Hobbes 


186  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

incurred  the  blame ;  but,  at  least,  lie  was  so  far 
pursuing  the  truly  scientific  method.  Up  to  this 
point,  indeed,  he  was  taking  the  line  which  would 
be  followed  by  a  modern  inquirer  into  the  history  of 
institutions.  Warfare  is  part  of  the  struggle  for 
existence  out  of  which  grow  states  and  the  whole 
organisation  of  civilised  societies.  A  modern  would 
maintain,  like  Hobbes,  that  in  admitting  the  part 
played  by  selfish  force  in  the  development  of  society, 
he  does  not  assert  the  wickedness  of  human  nature. 
He  only  asserts  that  the  good  impulses  cannot  acquire 
the  desirable  supremacy  until  a  peaceful  order  has  been 
established  by  the  complex  struggles  and  alliances 
of  human  beings,  swayed  by  all  their  passions  and 
ambitions.  But  here  we  come  upon  an  element  in 
Hobbes's  theory  of  which  I  have  already  spoken, 
namely,  the  Law  of  Nature.  The  "laws  of  human 
nature,"  in  the  scientific  sense,  expressing  the  way  in 
which  human  beings  actually  behave,  are  identified 
with  the  Law  of  Nature  as  an  ideal  or  divine  law, 
which  declares  how  men  ought  to  behave.  Hobbes 
professes  to  show  that  the  sovereign  has  certain 
"  rights '  as  well  as  certain  powers ;  and,  moreover, 
that  those  rights  are  far  from  being  recognised  in 
many  countries  and  especially  in  England.  He  is  not 
_  simply  pointing  out  how  it  came  to  pass  that  Charles  I. 
and  his  parliament  had  got  into  conflict,  and  thence 
inferring  the  best  mode  of  settling  the  disputed 
points ;  but  he  desires  to  show  that  the  "  Law  of 
Nature '  decides  the  question  of  their  conflicting 
rights.  The  "  Nature ):  which  prescribes  the  right 
cannot  be  identical  with  the  "  Nature '  which  gives 
the  power  and  determines  the  facts. 


iv.]  THE   STATE  187 

Hobbes's  next  point,  therefore,  is  to  show  what  are 
the  "  Laws  of  Nature."  Every  man  has  a  right,  he 
says,  to  use  his  own  power  for  his  own  preservation. 
A  "  Law  of  Nature  "  is  a  precept  found  out  by  reason, 
forbidding  him  to  do  the  contrary :  that  is,  to  destroy 
himself  or  his  means  of  self-preservation.  Now,  in  the 
"  state  of  nature ':  just  described,  every  man  has  a 
right  to  everything — even  to  another  man's  body. 
He  has  a  "  right,"  that  is,  because  nature  makes  self- 
preservation  the  sole  aim  of  each  man,  even  when  it 
implies  the  destruction  of  others.  But  it  is  plain  that, 
while  this  is  the  case,  no  man's  life  or  happiness  is 
secure.  "Nature,"  therefore,  orders  men  to  get  out 
of  the  "  state  of  nature  "  as  soon  as  they  can.  Hence 
we  have  the  twofold  principle.  It  is  the  "  fundamental 
law  of  nature  "  that  every  man  should  "  seek  peace  and 
follow  it "  ;  and  the  fundamental  "  right  of  nature  "  is 
that  a  man  should  defend  himself  by  every  means  he 
can.  Peace  makes  self-defence  easy.  It  follows  that 
a  man  should  "  lay  down  his  right  to  all  things  "  if 
other  men  will  lay  down  theirs.  This  is  identified  by 
Hobbes  with  the  "  law  of  the  Gospel "  :  "  Whatsoever 
you  require  that  others  should  do  to  you,  that  do  ye  to  them" 
or  (which  he  takes  to  be  equivalent),  "  Quod  tibi  fieri 
non  vis  alteri  ne  feceris."  A  man  may  simply  renounce 
or  he  may  transfer  a  right.  In  either  case,  he  is  said  to 
be  "obliged"  not  to  interfere  with  the  exercise  of  a  right 
by  those  to  whom  he  has  abandoned  or  granted  it. 
It  is  his  "duty"  not  to  make  his  grant  void  by  hinder- 
ing men  from  using  the  right ;  and  such  hindrance 
is  called  "  injustice."  We  thus  have  Hobbes's  defini- 
tions of  Obligation,  Duty,  and  Justice.  Injustice,  he 
observes,  is  like  an  absurdity  in  logic.  It  is  a  contra- 


188  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

diction  of  what  you  had  voluntarily  asserted  that  you 
would  do. 

From  these  definitions,  Hobbes  proceeds  to  deduce 
other  "Laws  of  Nature,"  and  finds  no  less  than 
nineteen.  The  third  law  (after  those  prescribing 
peace  and  self-defence)  is  that  men  should  keep  their 
"  covenants."  He  afterwards  deduces  the  duties 
of  gratitude,  sociability,  admission  of  equality  —  the 
breach  of  which  is  pride  —  equity,  and  so  forth.  If,  he 
says,  the  "deduction"  seems  "too  subtile,"  they  may 
all  be  regarded  as  corollaries  from  the  "  golden  rule." 
That  rule,  however,  is  itself  deducible  from  the  rule  of 
"  self-preservation."  We  do  good  to  others  in  order 
that  they  may  do  good  to  us.  "No  man  giveth,"  as 
he  says,  by  way  of  proving  that  gratitude  is  a  virtue, 
"  but  with  intention  of  good  to  himself."  ..."  Of 
all  voluntary  acts,  the  object  is  to  every  man  his  own 
good."  That,  one  would  rather  have  supposed,  is  a 
reason  for  not  being  "  grateful ';  to  anybody.  We 
must  interpret  "  gratitude  "  in  the  prospective  sense  — 
with  an  eye  to  the  favours  to  come.  It  is  prudent  to 
pay  your  debts  in  order  to  keep  up  your  credit.  In 
one  case  he  seems  to  deviate  a  little  from  his  egoism. 
Justice  means  keeping  covenants  —  obedience,  that  is, 
to  his  "  third  law."  A  man  who  does  a  just  action 
from  fear,  as  he  remarks,  is  not  therefore  a  just  man  ; 
his  "will  is  not  framed  by  the  justice,  but  by  the 
apparent  benefit  of  what  he  is  to  do.  That  which 
gives  to  human  actions  the  relish  of  justice  is  a  certain 
nobleness  or  gallantness  of  courage,  rarely  found,  by 
which  a  man  scorns  to  be  beholden  for  the  contentment 
of  his  life  to  fraud  or  breach  of  promise."  He  should 
have  held,  it  would  seem,  that  the  will  is  always 


iv.]  THE   STATE  189 

framed  by  the  "apparent  benefit."  The  inconsistency 
(if  there  be  one,  for  even  this  appears  to  be  a  case  of 
"  glory  ")  is  explicable.  Hobbes  has  to  deduce  all  the 
"  Laws  of  Nature  "  from  the  law  of  self-preservation. 
That,  no  doubt,  may  show  the  expediency  of  making 
a  "  covenant '  with  your  neighbours,  and  even  the 
expediency  of  generally  keeping  it.  But  it  must  also 
be  granted  that  there  are  occasions  in  which  expediency 
is  in  favour  of  breaking  covenants.  The  just  man,  the 
ordinary  moralist  would  say,  is  a  man  who  keeps  his 
word  even  to  his  own  disadvantage.  That,  on  the 
strictest  interpretation  of  Hobbes,  is  impossible.  No- 
body can  do  it.  Justice,  however,  in  the  sense  of 
"  covenant-keeping,"  is  so  essential  a  part  of  his  system, 
that  he  makes  an  implicit  concession  to  a  loftier  tone 
of  morality,  and  admits  that  a  man  may  love  justice 
for  its  own  sake.  This,  however,  seems  to  be  an  over- 
sight. Hobbes  is  content  to  take  for  granted  that 
each  man  will  profit  by  that  which  is  favourable  to 
all,  or  that  the  desire  for  self-preservation  will  always 
make  for  the  preservation  of  society.  The  Law  of 
Nature,  we  see,  is  simply  an  application  of  the  purely 
egoistic  law  of  self-preservation.  It  represents  the 
actual  forces  which  (in  Hobbes's  view)  mould  and 
regulate  all  human  institutions.  But  in  sanctioning 
so  respectable  a  virtue  as  "justice,"  it  takes  a  certain 
moral  colouring,  and  may  stand  for  the  ideal  Law  of 
Nature  or  Keason  to  which  the  actual  order  ought  to 
conform. 

There  is  another  reserve  to  be  made :  the  laws  of 
nature  are  not  properly  laws.  They  are  only  "  theorems 
concerning  what  conduceth  "  to  self-preservation.  They 
become  laws  proper  when  they  are  "  delivered  in  the 


190  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Word  of  God" ;  and  he  proceeds  in  the  De  Give  to  prove 
them  by  a  number  of  texts,  and  comes  to  the  edifying 
conclusion  that  the  "Law  of  Nature"  is  the  Law  of 
Christ.  It  is  a  theorem,  for  example,  that  to  keep  your 
word  tends  to  self-preservation.  But  law  means  the  com- 
mand of  a  rightful  superior ;  and  until  such  a  command 
has  been  given,  it  is  not  properly  a  "  Law  of  Nature '' 
that  you  should  keep  your  word.  The  laws  are  always 
binding  inforo  interno :  you  are  always  bound  to  desire 
that  they  should  come  into  operation ;  but  they  are 
not  always  binding  inforo  externo  ;  that  is,  you  are  not 
always  bound  to  "  put  them  in  act."  Self-preservation 
is  the  fundamental  law.  But  till  other  people  keep 
the  laws,  obedience  to  them  does  not  tend  to  self- 
preservation.  If  you  are  peaceful  and  truthful  when 
other  men  are  not,  you  will  "  procure  your  own  certain 
ruin,  contrary  to  all  the  Laws  of  Nature."  That 
obviously  will  be  the  case  in  the  "  state  of  nature  ': 
where  fraud  and  force  are  the  cardinal  virtues.  There 
is,  no  doubt,  a  truth  in  this  contention.  The  moral 
law,  to  become  operative  in  fact,  requires  a  certain 
amount  of  reciprocity.  Actual  morality  clearly  de- 
pends upon  the  stage  of  social  evolution.  In  a 
primitive  society,  where  men  have  to  defend  them- 
selves by  the  strong  hand,  we  can  hardly  condemn 
the  man  who  accepts  the  standard  methods.  Achilles 
would  be  a  brutal  ruffian  to-day ;  but  when  Troy  was 
besieged,  he  was  a  hero  deserving  admiration.  He 
was  perhaps  in  the  true  line  of  development.  The 
chief  of  a  savage  tribe  is,  on  the  whole,  preparing  the 
way  for  a  peaceful  order.  Even  in  the  present  day 
a  philanthropist  living  in  one  of  the  regions  where  the 
first-comer  is  ready  to  shoot  him  at  sight,  might  think 


iv.]  THE    STATE  191 

it  right  to  carry  a  revolver  in  his  pocket,  and,  if  neces- 
sary, to  anticipate  the  shooting.  Moral  rules  become 
useful  in  proportion  as  society  perceives  their  value, 
and  is  more  or  less  inclined  to  adopt  them,  in  practice. 
Otherwise,  the  man  whose  morality  was  of  a  higher 
type  would  be  thrown  away  or  summarily  stamped  out. 
Ought  a  man  to  be  several  generations  in  advance  of 
his  time?  That  is  a  pretty  problem  which  I  do  not 
undertake  to  solve.  In  any  case,  Hobbes  had  a  real 
and  important  meaning.  He  saw,  that  is,  that  the 
development  of  morality  implies  the  growth  of  a 
certain  understanding  between  the  individuals  com- 
posing the  society,  and  that  until  this  has  been  reached 
ideal  morality  proper  to  a  higher  plane  of  thought  is 
impracticable  if  not  undesirable.  This  leads  to  the 
theory  of  the  social  contract  —  the  mutual  agreement 
by  which  the  great  Leviathan  is  constructed. 

The  Law  of  Nature  prescribes  peace  as  a  condition 
of  security.  But  the  law  is  "contrary  to  our  natural 
passions,"  and  "  covenants  without  the  sword  are  but 
words  and  of  no  strength  to  secure  a  man  at  all."  It 
is  therefore  essential  to  create  a  common  power  to 
keep  men  in  awe.  Such  creatures  as  bees  and  ants 
do,  indeed,  live  at  peace  with  each  other  and  are 
therefore  called  by  Aristotle  "political  creatures." 
Why  cannot  men  do  so  ?  Because  men  compete  and 
have  private  aims  different  from  the  common  good. 
Men  too  can  talk  and  therefore  reason ;  they  are 
"  most  troublesome  when  most  at  ease,"  because  they 
then  love  to  show  their  wisdom  and  control  their 
rulers.  The  great  difference,  however,  is  that  their 
agreement  is  "  by  covenant,  which  is  artificial," 
whereas  bees  agree  by  "  nature."  By  "  artificial ' 


192  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

we  must  here  understand  what  is  made  by  reason. 
Since  men  can  live,  for  they  do  sometimes  live  in 
a  "  state  of  nature,"  a  political  society  is  not  essential 
to  man  as  man.  It  is  a  product  of  his  voluntary 
action,  and  therefore  implies  a  conscious  deliberation. 
The  only  way,  then,  in  which  the  common  power  can 
be  erected  and  security  established,  is  that  men  should 
"  confer  all  their  power  and  strength  upon  one  man 
or  one  assembly  of  men."  Then  wills  will  be  "reduced 
into  one  will,  and  every  man  acknowledge  himself  to 
be  the  author  of  whatsoever  is  done  by  the  ruler  so 
constituted."  "  This  is  more  than  consent  or  concord ; 
it  is  a  real  unity  of  them  all  in  one  and  the  same 
person,  made  by  covenant  of  every  man  with  every 
man ;  in  such  manner  as  if  every  man  should  say  to 
every  man :  ( I  authorise  and  give  up  my  right  of  govern- 
ing myself  to  this  man,  or  this  assembly  of  men,  on  this 
condition  that  thou  glue  up  thy  right  to  him,  and  authorise 
all  his  actions  in  like  manner.'  The  Leviathan,  or  mortal 
god,  is  instituted  by  this  covenant.  He  is  the  vital 
principle  of  political  association,  and  from  it  Hobbes 
will  proceed  to  deduce  the  whole  of  his  doctrine. 

Before  considering  its  terms,  one  remark  may  be 
made.  It  is  sometimes  asked  whether  the  expounders 
of  the  "  social  contract "  in  various  forms  meant  to  be 
understood  historically.  Did  they  mean  to  assert  that 
at  some  remote  period  a  number  of  men  had  held  a 
convention,  like  the  American  States,  and  signed 
articles  of  association,  to  bind  themselves  and  their 
posterity?  Occasionally  they  seem  to  be  driven  to 
accept  that  position.  Hobbes,  however,  can  hardly 
have  entertained  such  a  belief.  He  is  as  ready  as 
anybody  to  give  an  historical  account  of  the  origin 


iv.]  THE    STATE  193 

of  actual  constitutions.  In  his  Dialogue  upon  the 
Common  Law,  for  example,  he,  like  Montesquieu, 
traces  the  origin  of  the  British  Constitution  to  the 
forests  of  Germany,  and  the  system  once  prevalent 
among  the  "  savage  and  heathen ':  Saxons.  He  re- 
cognises in  the  Leviathan  that  governments  may  arise 
from  conquest  or  the  development  of  the  family  as 
well  as  by  "  institution,"  and  endeavours  to  show  that 
the  nature  of  sovereignty  will  be  the  same  in  whatever 
way  it  may  have  originated.  A  contract,  it  always 
has  to  be  admitted,  may  be  "  implicit  "  (that  is,  may 
really  be  no  contract  at  all),  and  there  can  be  no  doubt 
that,  in  point  of  fact,  the  social  contract,  if  it  exists, 
must  at  the  present  day  be  of  that  kind.  Nobody  is 
ever  asked  whether  he  will  or  will  not  agree  to  it. 
Men,  as  members  of  a  political  society,  accept  a  certain 
relation  to  the  sovereign,  and  unless  they  did  so  the 
society  would  be  dissolved.  That  such  an  understand- 
ing exists,  and  is  a  condition  of  the  existence  of 
the  State,  would  be  enough  for  Hobbes,  whatever  the 
origin  of  the  understanding.  As  we  shall  presently 
see,  he  would  be  more  consistent,  if  not  more  edifying, 
if  he  threw  the  contract  overboard  altogether. 

We  must  look  more  closely  at  the  terms  of  the 
hypothetical  contract.  The  first  point  is  that  Hobbes's 
version  differs  from  the  earlier  forms  in  this,  that  it  is 
not  a  contract  between  the  subject  and  the  sovereign, 
but  between  the  subjects  themselves.  The  sovereign 
is  created  by  it,  but  is  not  a  party  to  it.  This  is 
Hobbes's  special  and  most  significant  contribution  to 
the  theory.  His  reason  is  plain.  Men,  in  a  state 
of  nature,  that  is,  not  acknowledging  any  common 
authority,  cannot  make  a  contract  collectively.  They 


194  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

are,  in  that  case,  simply  a  "multitude."  His  own 
theory,  he  says  in  a  note  to  the  De  Give,  depends  upon 
clearly  understanding  the  different  senses  in  which 
this  word  may  be  used.  A  multitude  means  first  a 
multitude  of  men.  Each  has  his  own  will  and  can 
make  compacts  with  his  neighbours.  There  may  be 
as  many  compacts  as  there  are  men,  or  pairs  of  men, 
but  there  is  then  no  such  thing  as  a  common  will  or 
a  contract  of  the  multitude  considered  as  a  unit. 
This  first  becomes  possible  when  they  have  each  agreed 
that  the  will  of  some  one  man  or  of  a  majority  shall 
be  taken  for  the  will  of  all.  Then  the  multitude 
becomes  a  "person,"  and  is  generally  called  a  "  people." 
One  man  is  a  "natural  person,"  and  their  common 
representative  is  an  "  artificial  person,"  or,  as  he  puts 
it,  "  bears  the  person  of  the  people."  It  is,  therefore, 
impossible  to  take  the  social  contract  as  made  between 
the  sovereign  and  the  subjects.  Till  they  have  become 
an  "artificial  person ';  they  cannot  make  a  contract  as 
a  whole.  This  social  contract  is  presupposed  in  all 
other  contracts.  It  must  be  at  the  foundation  of  all 
corporate  action,  and  a  compact  between  the  sovereign 
and* the  subjects  would  suppose  the  previous  existence 
of  a  unity  which  is  only  created  by  the  contract  itself. 
In  the  "state  of  nature"  men  can  promise  but  cannot 
make  a  binding  contract.  A  contract  means  an  ex- 
change of  promises,  and  in  a  "  state  of  nature  "  neither 
party  can  depend  upon  the  other  keeping  his  word. 
Obligation  follows  security.  It  seems  rather  difficult, 
perhaps,  to  see  how  you  can  ever  get  out  of  the  state 
of  nature,  or  why  the  agreement  of  each  man  to  take 
the  sovereign  will  for  his  own,  is  more  likely  to  be 
observed  than  any  other  agreement.  Hobbes,  how- 


iv.]  THE   STATE  195 

ever,  assumes  that  tliis  is  possible ;  and  when  the 
Leviathan  has  once  been  constructed,  it  embodies  the 
common  will.  The  multitude  becomes  a  person,  and 
law,  natural  and  civil,  becomes  binding. 

3.   "  Tlie  Leviathan  " 

We  have  thus  got  our  sovereign.  His  will  is  the 
will  of  all.  He  is  under  no  obligation  to  his  subjects, 
but  is  the  source  of  all  obligation.  The  ultimate 
justification  of  his  existence,  however,  is  still  the  desire 
for  self-preservation,  and  for  peace  as  an  essential 
condition.  Hence,  indeed,  arise  the  only  limitations 
to  the  power  of  the  sovereign  which  Hobbes  admits. 
Since  I  aim  at  my  own  security,  I  cannot  lay  down 
the  right  of  resisting  men  who  would  kill  me,  or  even 
men  "  who  would  inflict  wounds  or  imprisonment." 
I  may  indeed  agree  that  you  shall  kill  me,  but  I 
cannot  agree  that  I  will  not  resist  you.  A  criminal 
may  be  properly  put  to  death,  for  he  has  agreed 
to  the  law ;  but  he  must  be  guarded  on  his  way  to 
execution,  for  he  has  not  bargained  not  to  run 
away.  He  adds  another  quaint  exception.  A  man 
may  refuse  to  serve  as  a  soldier,  at  least  if  he 
can  offer  a  substitute.  "And,"  he  adds,  "there  is 
allowance  to  be  made  for  natural  timorousness,  not 
only  to  women,  of  whom  no  such  dangerous  duty  is  ex- 
pected, but  also  to  men  of  feminine  courage."  (They 
may  have  been  born  in  1588.)  In  such  cases,  it  seems, 
disobedience  does  not  "frustrate  the  end  for  which 
sovereignty  was  ordained."  The  principle  applies  to 
the  case  of  de  facto  government  —  when  the  sovereign 
cannot  defend  me  I  need  not  obey  him. 


196  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

With  these  exceptions,  the  power  of  the  sovereign 
is  unlimited.  The  "mortal  god"  is  omnipotent.  The 
covenant  once  made  is  indefeasible.  The  parties  to 
it  cannot  make  a  new  covenant  inconsistent  with  it. 
They  cannot  transfer  their  allegiance  without  the 
consent  of  the  sovereign.  Since  there  is  no  power  of 
revising  the  covenant,  it  cannot  be  broken  without 
injustice.  Hobbes,  we  see,  speaks  of  the  sovereign 
as  "representing'1  the  subjects.  But  he  does  not 
"represent"  them  as  a  member  of  parliament  repre- 
sents his  constituents,  or  as  a  delegate  bound  to  carry 
out  their  wishes.  He  "  represents  "  them  in  the  sense 
that  whatever  he  does  is  taken  to  be  done  by  them. 
They  are  as  responsible  for  all  his  actions  as  though 
he  was  their  volition  incorporated.  It  follows  that 
his  power  can  never  be  forfeited.  The  subjects  have 
done  whatever  he  has  done,  and  in  resisting  him 
would  be  calling  themselves  to  account.  The  social 
contract,  considered  as  a  covenant  with  the  ruler,  was 
alleged  as  a  justification  of  rebellion.  Hobbes  inverts 
the  argument.  It  can  never  be  right  to  allege  a 
"covenant"  with  the  ruler  because  that  would  justify 
rebellion.  Since  there  is  no  common  judge  in  such  a 
case,  this  would  mean  an  appeal  to  the  power  of  the 
sword,  and  the  power  of  the  sword  is  what  you  have 
abandoned  in  covenanting.  No  individual  again  can 
dissent.  If  he  does,  he  "may  justly  be  destroyed '• 
by  the  rest.  If  he  consented  to  covenant,  he  implicitly 
consented  to  the  covenant  actually  made.  But,  if 
not,  he  is  left  in  the  state  of  nature  and  may,  there- 
fore, "without  injustice  be  destroyed  by  any  man 
whatsoever." 

The  Leviathan,  thus  constituted,  has  therefore  an 


iv.]  THE   STATE  197 

indefeasible* title  and  is  irresponsible.  He  is  the 
ultimate  authority  from  whom  all  rights  are  derived. 
The  end  of  his  institution  is  peace.  A  right  to  the  end 
implies  a  right  to  the  means.  The  sovereign  may  do 
whatever  promotes  peace.  Since  men's  actions  proceed 
from  their  opinions,  he  may  suppress  the  publication  of 
opinions  tending  in  his  opinion  to  disturb  the  peace. 
Since  contention  arises  from  the  clashing  of  rights,  he 
must  determine  men's  rights  ;  or,  in  other  words,  must 
be  the  supreme  legislator.  The  law  means  the  com- 
mand of  the  sovereign,  and  whatever  he  commands  is 
therefore  law.  He  must,  again,  have  the  "  right  of  judi- 
cature " ;  the  right  to  hear  and  decide  all  controversies 
arising  out  of  the  law.  The  sword  of  justice  belongs 
to  him,  and  "the  sword  of  justice  must  go  with  the 
sword  of  war."  The  sovereign  has  to  protect  the 
people  against  foreign  enemies  as -well  as  to  protect 
each  man  against  his  neighbour.  He  must  decide  upon 
war  and  peace  ;  and  when  war  is  necessary  must  decide 
what  forces  are  necessary ;  and,  further,  must  decide 
how  much  money  is  required  to  pay  for  them.  "The 
command  of  the  militia  "  (the  military  forces  in  general), 
"  without  other  institution,  maketh  him  that  hath  it 
sovereign ;  and,  therefore,  whosoever  is  made  general 
of  an  army,  he  that  hath  the  sovereign  power  is  always 
generalissimo."  Other  powers,  such  as  the  appoint- 
ment of  ministers,  the  distribution  of  honours,  and  the 
infliction  of  punishments,  obviously  follow. 

The  Leviathan,  thus  invested  with  fullest  power  of 
legislature,  judicature,  and  military  command,  with 
authority  over  opinion,  and  right  to  levy  taxes, 
appeared  to  Hobbes's  contemporaries  to  be  a  terrible 
portent.  Charles  I.,  trying  to  dispense  with  parlia- 


198  HOBBES  [CHA.P. 

ments,  Cromwell  ruling  by  armed  force,  Louis  XIV. 
declaring  himself  to  be  the  State,  might  be  taken  as 
avatars  of  the  monster.  Lovers  of  liberty  of  thought 
or  action  were  shocked  by  a  doctrine  fit  only  for  the 
graceless  and  abject  courtiers  of  the  Restoration.  The 
doctrine,  however,  must  be  considered  on  more  general 
grounds.  Hobbes,  in  the  first  place,  is  not  here  arguing 
for  one  form  of  government  more  than  for  another. 
He  prefers  monarchy ;  but  his  special  point  is  that  in 
every  form,  monarchic,  aristocratic,  or  democratic,  there 
must  be  a  "  sovereign  "  -  an  ultimate,  supreme,  and 
single  authority.  Men,  he  says,  admit  the  claim  of  a 
popular  State  to  "  absolute  dominion,"  but  object  to 
the  claim  of  a  king,  though  he  has  the  same  power  and 
is  not  more  likely,  for  reasons  given,  to  abuse  it.  The 
doctrine  which  he  really  opposes  is  that  of  a  "  mixed 
government."  As  "  some  doctors  "  hold  that  there  are 
three  souls  in  one  man,  others  hold  that  there  can  be 
more  souls  than  one  in  a  commonwealth.  That  is 
virtually  implied  when  they  say  that  "  the  power  of 
levying  money,  which  is  the  nutritive  faculty,"  depends 
on  a  "  general  assembly  "  ;  the  "  power  of  conduct  and 
command,  which  is  the  motive  faculty,  on  one  man ;  and 
the  power  of  making  laws,  which  is  the  rational  faculty, 
on  the  accidental  consent,  not  only  of  those  two  last,  but 
of  a  third  "  :  this  is  called  "  mixed  monarchy."  "  In 
truth  it  is  not  one  independent  commonwealth,  but  three 
independent  factions ;  nor  one  representative  person 
but  three.  In  the  Kingdom  of  God  there  may  be 
three  persons  independent  without  breach  of  unity  in 
God  that  reigneth ;  but  where  men  reign  that  be  sub- 
ject to  diversity  of  opinions,  it  cannot  be  so.  And 
therefore  if  the  king  bear  the  person  of  the  people,  the 


iv.]  THE   STATE  199 

general  assembly  bear  the  person  of  the  people,  and 
another  assembly  bear  the  person  of  a  part  of  the 
people,  they  are  not  one  person,  nor  one  sovereign,  but 
three  persons  and  three  sovereigns."  That  is  to  say, 
the  political,  like  the  animal  organism,  is  essentially 
a  unit.  So  far  as  there  is  not  somewhere  a  supreme 
authority,  there  is  anarchy  or  a  possibility  of  anarchy. 
The  application  to  Hobbes's  own  times  is  obvious.  The 
king,  for  example,  has  a  right  to  raise  ship-money  in 
case  of  necessity.  But  who  has  a  right  to  decide  the 
question  of  necessity  ?  If  the  king,  he  could  raise 
taxes  at  pleasure.  If  the  parliament,  the  king  becomes 
only  their  pensioner.  At  the  bottom  it  was  a  question 
of  sovereignty,  and  Hobbes,  holding  the  king  to  be 
sovereign,  holds  that  Hanipden  showed  "  an  ignorant 
impatience  of  taxation."  "  Mark  the  oppression  !  A 
parliament  man  of  £500  a  year,  land-taxed  20s." 
Hampden  was  refusing  to  contribute  to  his  own  de- 
fence. "  All  men  are  by  nature  provided  of  notable 
multiplying  glasses,  through  which  every  little  pay- 
ment appeareth  a  great  grievance."  Parliament  re- 
monstrated against  arbitrary  imprisonment,  the  Star 
Chamber,  and  so  forth ;  but  it  was  their  own  fault 
that  the  king  had  so  to  act.  Their  refusal  to  give 
money  "put  him  (the  king)  upon  those  extraordinary 
ways,  which  they  call  illegal,  of  raising  money  at  home." 
The  experience  of  the  Civil  War,  he  says  in  the 
Leviathan,  has  so  plainly  shown  the  mischief  of  dividing 
the  rights  of  the  sovereign  that  few  men  in  England 
fail  to  see  that  they  should  be  inseparable  and  should 
be  so  acknowledged  "  at  the  next  return  of  peace." 

Men  did  in  fact  come  to  acknowledge  it  though  not 
for  some  generations,  and  then  by  virtually  transferring 


200  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

sovereignty  from  the  king  to  the  parliament.  A 
confused  state  of  mind  in  the  interval  was  implied  in 
the  doctrine  which  long  prevailed,  of  the  importance 
of  a  division  between  the  legislative,  executive,  and 
judicial  powers,  and  in  the  doctrine  that  the  British 
Constitution  represented  a  judicious  mixture  of  the 
three  elements,  aristocracy,  monarchy,  and  democracy, 
whose  conflicts  were  regulated  by  an  admirable 
system  of  checks  and  balances.  Whatever  truth  may 
have  been  expressed  in  such  theories,  they  were 
erroneous  so  far  as  inconsistent  with  Hobbes's  doctrine. 
A  division  of  the  governmental  functions  is  of  course 
necessary,  and  different  classes  should  be  allowed  to 
exercise  an  influence  upon  the  State.  But  the  division 
of  functions  must  be  consistent  with  the  recognition  of 
a  single  authority  which  can  regulate  and  correlate 
their  powers ;  and  a  contest  between  classes,  which 
do  not  in  some  way  recognise  a  sovereign  arbitrator, 
leads  to  civil  war  or  revolution.  Who  is  the  sove- 
reign, for  example,  was  the  essential  question  which 
in  the  revolt  of  the  American  colonies,  and  in  the 
secession  of  the  Southern  States,  had  to  be  answered 
by  bullets.  So  long  as  that  question  is  open,  there  is 
a  condition  of  unstable  equilibrium  or  latent  anarchy. 
The  State,  as  Hobbes  puts  it,  should  have  only  one 
soul,  or  as  we  may  say,  the  political  organism  should 
have  the  unity  corresponding  to  a  vital  principle. 

The  unity  of  the  Leviathan  seemed  to  imply  arbi- 
trary power.  Since  the  king  had  the  power  of  the 
sword,  said  Hobbes,  he  must  also  have  the  power  of 
the  purse.  The  logic  might  be  good,  but  might  be 
applied  the  other  way.  The  true  Englishman  was 
determined  not  to  pay  the  money  till  he  knew  how  it 


iv.]  THE   STATE  201 

was  to  be  spent ;  and  complained  of  a  loss  of  liberty  if 
it  was  taken  by  force.  Hobbes's  reply  to  this  is  very 
forcible  and  clears  his  position.  He  agreed  with  John- 
son that  the  cry  for  liberty  was  cant.  .'  What,  he  asks, 
in  his  De  Cive,  is  meant  by  liberty  ?  If  an  exemption 
from  the  laws,  it  can  exist  in  no  government  whatever. 
If  it  consist  in  having  few  laws,  and  only  those  such  as 
are  necessary  to  peace,  there  is  no  more  liberty  in  a 
democracy  than  in  a  monarchy.  What  men  really 
demand  is  not  liberty  but  "  dominion."  People  are 
deceived  because  in  a  democracy  they  have  a  greater 
share  in  public  offices  or  in  choosing  the  officers.  It 
does  not  follow  that  they  have  more  liberty  in  the 
sense  of  less  law.  Hobbes  was  putting  his  finger 
upon  an  ambiguity  which  has  continued  to  flourish. 
Liberty  may  either  mean  that  a  man  is  not  bound  by 
law  or  that  he  is  only  bound  by  laws  which  he  has 
made  (or  shared  in  making)  himself.  We  are  quite 
aware  at  the  present  day  that  a  democracy  may  use 
the  liberty,  which  in  one  sense  it  possesses,  by  making 
laws  which  are  inconsistent  with  liberty  in  the  other 
sense. 

J  The  problem,  so  much  discussed  in  our  times,  as 
to  the  proper  limits  of  government  interference  had 
not  then  excited  attention.  Hobbes  seems  to  incline 
towards  non-interference.  Subjects  grow  rich,  he  says, 
by  "  the  fruits  of  the  earth  and  water,  labour  and 
thrift"  (land,  labour,  and  capital),  and  the  laws  should 
encourage  industry  and  forbid  extravagance.  The 
"  impotent "  should  be  supported  and  the  able-bodied 
set  to  work ;  taxes  should  be  equal,  and  laid  upon  con- 
sumption, which  (as  he  thinks)  will  encourage  saving, 
and  extravagance  should  be  punished.  So  far  his 


202  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

principles  are  those  which  his  contemporaries  fully 
accepted.  But  he  adds  emphatically  that  the  laws 
should  not  go  too  far.  "As  water  enclosed  on  all 
hands  with  banks,  stands  still  and  corrupts,  so 
subjects,  if  they  might  do  nothing  without  the 
command  of  the  law,  would  grow  dull  and  un- 
wieldy.'7 They  must  not,  however,  be  left  too  much 
to  themselves.  "  Both  extremes  are  faulty,  for  laws 
were  not  invented  to  take  away  but  to  direct  men's 
actions,  even  as  nature  ordained  the  banks  not  to  stay, 
but  to  guide  the  course  of  the  stream ;  it  is  therefore 
against  sound  policy  that  there  should  be  more  laws 
than  necessarily  serve  for  the  good  of  the  magistrate 
and  his  subjects."  Laws,  moreover,  should  be  clear, 
simple,  and  directed  not  to  revenge,  but  to  correction. 
"  Leaders  of  a  commotion  should  be  punished ;  not 
the  poor  seduced  people.  To  be  severe  to  the  people, 
is  to  punish  that  ignorance  which  may  in  great  part 
be  imputed  to  the  sovereign,  whose  fault  it  was  that 
they  were  no  better  instructed."  This  is,  perhaps, 
the  only  remark  of  Hobbes  which  would  be  endorsed 
by  Tolstoi.  Hobbes  was  in  favour  of  a  despotic  rule ; 
but  he  was  anxious  that  it  should  be  thoroughly 
humane,  and  was  fully  sensible  that  the  English  laws 
were  in  great  need  of  reform. 

Such  questions,  however,  were  then  in  the  back- 
ground. The  real  issue  with  his  contemporaries  was 
different.  Although  his  theory  of  sovereignty  is 
avowedly  independent  of  the  particular  form  of  govern- 
ment, he  has  a  leaning  to  monarchy.  He  confesses 
that  he  has  not  proved  this  advantage  demonstratively : 
"the  one  thing  in  the  whole  book,"  he  adds,  in  regard 
to  which  he  will  make  that  modest  admission.  His 


iv.]  THE   STATE  203 

grounds  are  mainly  that  a  king  has  a  direct  interest 
in  promoting  the  welfare  of  his  subjects,  while  popular 
leaders  are  prompted  by  vain  glory  and  jealousy  of 
each  other,  and  popular  assemblies  are  swayed  by 
orators,  for  whom  he  always  expresses  contempt.  "  A 
democracy  is  no  more  than  an  aristocracy  of  orators, 
interrupted  sometimes  with  the  temporary  monarchy 
of  one  orator " :  a  Pym  or  a  Gladstone.  Hobbes's 
dislike  to  popular  rule  may  be  due  in  part  to  a  certain 
intellectual  difficulty.  A  sovereign  must  needs  be  a 
unit.  But  Hobbes  is  not  comfortable  with  abstractions, 
or  with  so  vague  a  body  as  the  sovereign  in  a  complex 
political  system.  He  likes  to  have  a  king  — a  concrete, 
tangible  individual  in  whom  his  principles  may  be 
incarnated.  This  prevents  him  from  recognising  one 
development  of  his  theory  which  none  the  less  was 
implied  from  the  first.  He  perceives  with  perfect 
clearness  and  asserts  in  the  most  vigorous  way  that 
the  division  of  sovereignty  was  the  real  weakness  of  the 
English  system.  His  prejudices  lead  him  to  throw 
the  whole  blame  upon  the  popular  leaders.  But  a  man 
of  science  should  see  that  it  is  little  to  the  purpose  to 
blame  individuals.  Their  discontent  is  a  fact :  a  philo- 
sophical reformer  should  aim  not  at  denouncing  the 
symptoms,  but  at  removing  the  causes  of  discord.  It 
was  clearly  hopeless  to  persuade  either  side  that  it  was 
in  the  wrong;  but  he  might  have  tried  to  give  an 
impartial  *  diagnosis  of  the  disease.  He  might  then 
have  admitted  that  the  true  solution  might  be,  not 
to  give  the  power  of  the  purse  to  the  king,  but  to  give 
the  power  of  the  sword  to  the  parliament.  If  he  had 
contemplated  that  proposition,  he  might  have  foreseen 
(I  do  not  mean  that  any  human  being  could  wholly 


204  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

have   foreseen)   that   his    theory   would    apply   to  a 
radically  changed  order. 

In  fact,  Hobbes's  Leviathan  represents  what  is  called 
"the  modern  State."  Supremacy  of  the  law,  absolute 
authority  of  the  governing  power,  and  unity  of  the 
administrative  system  may  be  most  fully  realised  when 
the  "  sovereign  "  is  not  an  individual  but  an  organic 
body.  Government  represents  or  "bears  the  person 
of  the  people,"  not  in  Hobbes's  sense,  that  whatsoever 
the  sovereign  wills  becomes  their  will,  but  in  the  inverse 
sense,  that  whatever  they  will  becomes  his  will.  Similar 
consequences  follow  in  either  version.  Hobbes,  for 
example,  believes  in  the  equality  of  man.  It  is  one 
of  his  laws  of  nature  that  "  every  man  acknowledge 
another  for  his  equal  by  nature."  Even  if  men  were 
not  equal,  they  would  only  make  the  compact  on  con- 
ditions of  equality.  Inequality  of  subjects,  he  says 
elsewhere,  is  made  by  the  sovereign ;  and  therefore 
all  must  be  equal  before  the  sovereign,  as  kings  and 
subjects  are  equal  before  the  King  of  Kings.  Crimes 
of  great  men  are  "  not  extenuated  but  aggravated  by 
the  greatness  of  their  persons."  If  they  are  favoured, 
"  impunity  maketh  insolence  ;  insolence  hatred  ;  and 
hatred  an  endeavour  to  pull  down  all  oppressing  and 
contumelious  greatness,  though  with  the  ruin  of  the 
commonwealth."  No  subject  can  acquire  any  rights 
which  will  impede  the  full  exercise  of  the  sovereign 
power.  The  property  of  subjects  in  lands,  for  example, 
"consisteth  in  right  to  exclude  all  other  subjects  from 
the  use  of  them,  and  not  to  exclude  their  sovereign, 
be  it  an  assembly  or  a  monarch."  If  land  is  not  to  be 
nationalised,  the  landowner's  right  is  never  absolute. 
So  in  all  "  systems  subject  —  that  is,  in  all  associations 


iv.]  THE   STATE  205 

of  any  kind  —  no  power  can  be  enjoyed  except  what  the 
sovereign  chooses  to  allow."  They  must  be  thoroughly 
subordinate  to  his  will,  though  in  practice  they  have 
an  awkward  tendency  to  independence.  Among  the 
diseases  of  a  commonwealth,  Hobbes  reckons  great 
towns  able  to  furnish  an  army  (London,  of  course,  is 
in  his  mind)  "  as  well  as  the  great  number  of  corpora- 
tions which  are,  as  it  were,  many  lesser  commonwealths 
in  the  bowels  of  the  greater,  like  worms  in  the  entrails 
of  a  natural  man."  The  principle  is  evidently  fatal 
to  privileged  estates  or  corporations.  The  king  or 
sovereign  may  call  in  councillors ;  but  they  must 
remain  councillors  only.  That,  for  example,'  is  the 
case  with  the  House  of  Commons.  But  the  House  of 
Lords  has  no  better  claim.  "  Good  counsel  comes  not 
by  inheritance."  The  claim  of  certain  persons  to  have 
a  place  in  the  highest  council  by  inheritance  is  derived 
"  from  the  conquests  of  the  ancient  Germans."  Their 
chiefs  were  able  to  extract  privileges  for  their  posterity. 
Such  privileges,  however,  are  inconsistent  with  sove- 
reign power,  and  if  men  contend  for  them  as  a  right, 
they  "must  needs  by  degrees  let  them  go,"  and  be 
content  with  the  honour  due  to  their  natural  abilities.  / 

This  consequence  of  the  supremacy  of  the  sovereign 
illustrates  one  curious  contrast  between  Hobbes  and 
his  opponents.  The  parliamentary  party  had  to  defend 
privilege  against  prerogative  ;  and  privilege  has  to  be 
defended  by  precedent.  The  party,  therefore,  which 
would  in  modern  phrase  claim  to  be  the  "  party  of 
progress,"  justified  itself  by  appealing  to  antiquity. 
When,  indeed,  you  cut  off  a  king's  head  you  have  to 
appeal  to  general  principles.  Constitutional  precedents 
are  not  available.  Milton  had  to  claim  indefeasible 


206  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

rights  for  the  people,  and  men  like  honest  John  Lil- 
burne  used  language  which  anticipated  Paine's  Rights 
of  Man.  But  in  the  earlier  stages  of  the  quarrel,  Coke's 
gigantic  knowledge  of  old  records,  and  superstitious 
reverence  for  the  common  law,  that  is,  for  tradition 
and  custom,  was  a  stronghold  of  the  party.  Hobbes 
rejects  the  whole  doctrine.  An  absolute  political 
theory  could  not  fit  into  the  constitutional  tradition 
or  justify  the  heterogeneous  products  of  historical 
accidents.  His  treatise  on  the  common  law  expresses 
his  aversion  to  Coke.  He  had  already  quoted  him  in 
the  Leviathan  to  show  how  men's  judgments  were 
"  perverted  by  trusting  to  precedent."  "  If  the  man 
who  first  judged,  judged  unjustly,  no  injustice  can  be 
a  pattern  of  justice  to  succeeding  judges."  No  custom, 
again,  can  justify  itself.  If  "  use  obtaineth  the  autho- 
rity of  a  law,  it  is  not  the  length  of  time  that  maketh 
the  authority,  but  the  will  of  the  sovereign  signified 
by  his  silence."  The  tacit  consent  of  a  ruler  may  make 
a  custom  law.  But  "  many  unjust  actions  and  unjust 
sentences  go  uncontrolled  for  a  longer  time  than  any 
man  can  remember."  Only  "  reasonable "  customs 
should  be  law,  and  evil  customs  should  be  abolished. 
The  sovereign  must  decide  what  is  reasonable  and 
what  should  be  abolished. 

According  to  Hobbes,  then,  all  political  machinery 
is  absolutely  subordinate  to  the  sovereign.  His  power 
is  the  sole  working  force,  and  every  resisting  element 
must  be  ejected  or  brought  under  control.  The  law  is 
the  expression  of  his  will,  and  though  he  may  enforce 
rules  which  have  grown  up  independently,  they  can 
only  exist  on  sufferance  or  by  his  tacit  consent.  In 
that  respect  Hobbes  was  at  one  with  the  most  thorough- 


iv.]  THE    STATE  207 

going  revolutionists  who  ever  proposed  to  rearrange 
the  political  order  upon  an  ideal  plan,  and  to  abolish 
all  traditional  law  which  is  not  in  conformity  with  the 
dictates  of  reason.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  Hobbes's 
legal  doctrine  came  to  life  again  in  the  hands  of 
Benthain  and  his  follower,  Austin,  the  legal  lights  of 
the  "philosophical  radicals."  Maine  observes  that 
they  had  scarcely  anything  to  add  to  Hobbes's  analysis 
of  the  meaning  of  law.  Hobbes  puts  his  theory  with 
all  possible  clearness  in  the  De  Give  and  the  Leviathan. 
"  A  law  is  a  command  of  that  person,  whose  precept 
contains  in  it  the  reason  of  obedience."  The  "civil 
law  "  is  the  command  of  the  sovereign.  We  are  bound 
to  obey  it,  because  it  is  his  command,  as  soon  as  we 
know  it  to  be  his.  It  must  therefore  be  promulgated 
in  order  that  we  may  know  it,  and  have  a  "  penalty 
annexed  to  it "  in  order  that  we  may  obey  it ;  for 
"vain  is  that  law  which  may  be  broken  without 
punishment."  When  we  are  solemnly  informed  that 
a  law  is  a  command  of  the  sovereign,  enforced  by  a 
"  sanction,"  the  impulse  of  the  unregenerate  mind  is 
to  reply,  "  that  is  what  I  always  supposed."  Parlia- 
ment and  the  policeman  are  phenomena  too  obvious  to 
be  overlooked ;  the  great  manufactory  which  is  always 
turning  out  laws,  and  the  rod  which  will  smite  us  if 
we  do  not  obey  are  always  with  us.  What  else 
should  a  law  be  than  a  rule  made  by  one  and  enforced 
by  the  other  ?  We  are  told  in  reply  that  great  con- 
fusion has  arisen  by  confounding  such  laws  with  "  Laws 
of  Nature,"  laws  which  are  supposed  to  exist  in  some 
transcendental  world,  and  yet  to  supply  the  necessary 
basis  for  the  laws  of  actual  life,  and  which  have  to  be 
applied  to  life  by  the  help  of  such  shifty  and  ambigu- 


208  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

ous  hypotheses  as  the  social  contract.  I  do  not  doubt 
that  that  is  true,  but  it  suggests  one  question.  Austin 
and  his  disciples  were  always  exposing  the  absurdity 
of  the  Law  of  Nature  and  the  social  contract,  and  yet 
their  own  doctrine  coincides  with  that  of  Hobbes,  who 
professes  to  make  these  theories  an  integral  part  of 
his  system. 

The  explanation  is  simple,  and  gives  the  essence 
of  Hobbes.  According  to  Hobbes,  in  fact,  the 
Law  of  Nature  has  a  singularly  limited  sphere  of 
action.  It  only  exists,  one  may  say,  in  order  to  repeal 
itself.  Before  the  social  contract,  he  says,  every  man 
has  a  right  to  everything,  which  is  practically  equiva- 
lent to  nobody  having  a  right  to  anything ;  for  if  the 
same  thing  belongs  to  two  men,  neither  has  a  right 
against  the  other.  But  the  contract  is  itself  made  by 
every  man  resigning  all  his  rights  to  the  sovereign.  ,  \ 
When  he  has  thus  made  them  over,  he  can  no  longer 
make  any  claims  under  the  Law  of  Nature.  The 
sovereign  may  command  him  to  do  anything  (except, 
indeed,  to  help  to  hang  himself)  and  he  is  bound  to 
obey.  The  Law  of  Nature  orders  him  to  obey  the 
positive  law,  and  does  nothing  else.  This  comes, 
however,  of  being  thoroughly  logical,  after  making 
one  initial  error.  The  Law  of  Nature  is  simply  the 
law  of  self-preservation,  and  whatever  necessarily 
follows  from  it.  But  in  what  sense  of  "  law "  can 
we  call  self-preservation  a  law  ?  In  one  sense  it  is 
what  Hobbes  calls  a  "theorem,"  not  a  law.  It  is 
(assuming  its  truth)  a  statement  of  fact.  All  men 
do  aim  at  self-preservation.  That  is  their  one  actual 
and,  indeed,  their  one  possible  principle.  If  so,  it 
cannot  be  a  "law'  at  all  in  the  ethical  or  strictly 


iv.]  THE   STATE  209 

legal  sense.     It   expresses  an   essential   condition   of 
man's  nature,  and  not  a  law  imposed  upon  him  from 
without.    Men  act  for  their  own  preservation  as  stones 
fall  by  gravitation.     It  is  a  way  they  have,  and  they 
cannot  have  any  other.     Taking  for  granted  the  truth 
of  the  "theorem,"  it   will   enable   us   to   show  how 
political  institutions  and  "  civil  laws  "  have  come  into 
existence,  but  it  does  not  show  that  they  are  right 
or  wrong.     It  is  as  irrelevant  to  introduce  that  con- 
fusion as  it  would  be  to  say  that   the  angles  of   a 
triangle    ought    to    be    equal    to    two    right    angles. 
Hobbes's   real  theory  comes  out  when  we  drop  the 
imaginary   contract    altogether.      We   assume   "  self- 
preservation"  as  the  universal  instinct  and,  moreover, 
we  must  provisionally  accept  Hobbes's  thoroughgoing 
egoism.       Then    so    long    as    there    is    no    common 
superior,  the  instinct  produces  competition  and  war, 
and  implies   the   nasty,   brutish   "  state   of    nature." 
How  do  men  get  out  of  it  ?     Historically,  he  replies, 
governments  may  be  made  by  conquest  or  developed 
out  of  the  family,  "  which  is  a  little  monarchy."     In 
both  cases  sovereignty  is  acquired  by  "  force  "  and  the 
subjects   submit   from  fear.      Governments,  also,  are 
made  by  "  institution,"  that  is,  by  the  social  contract ; 
and  in  this  case  the  motive  is  still  fear,  but  fear  of  one 
another.     Admitting,  then,  that  even  as  an  historical 
fact,  sovereignty  has  been  made  by  "  institution  '•  or 
contract,  the  essential  motive  is  still  the  same.     Each 
man  sees  that  he  will  be  better  off,  or  preserve  his  life 
and  means  of  living  better  if  he  and  his  will  obey  a 
sovereign  than  if  they  remain  masterless.     The  hypo- 
thesis that  States  were  deliberately  contrived  and  made 
by  a  bargain  between  the  separate  atoms  is,  of  course, 


210  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

absurd  historically,  but  is  also  irrelevant  to  Hobbes. 
The  essential  point  is  simply  that  settled  order  is  so 
much  more  favourable  to  self-preservation  than  anarchy 
that  every  one  has  a  sufficient  interest  in  maintaining 
it.  Peace,  as  he  tells  us,  means  all  the  arts  and 
sciences  that  distinguish  Europeans  from  Choctaws. 
The  original  contractors  can  scarcely  be  supposed  to 
have  foreseen  that.  But  at  least  it  gives  a  very  good 
reason  for  obedience. 

This  comes  out  curiously  in  Hobbes's  "  exceptions  ' 
to  the  obligation  of  the  contract.  Men  are  not  bound 
to  kill  themselves  because  the  tacit  "  consideration ' 
for  accepting  the  contract  was  the  preservation  of  life 
and  the  means  of  life.  He  was  logically  bound  to  go 
further.  If  upon  that  ground  they  may  repudiate  the 
contract,  they  may  break  it  whenever  the  end  is  frus- 
trated, that  is,  whenever  by  keeping  it  they  will  be  in 
a  worse  position.  Moreover,  since  nobody  ever  acts, 
except  for  his  own  good,  they  certainly  will  break  it 
whether  it  is  binding  or  not.  In  other  words,  the 
supposed  contract  is  merely  another  version  of  the 
first  principle  of  egoism :  a  man  will  always  do  what 
seems  to  be  for  his  own  interest.  By  calling  it  a 
contract  he  gets  the  appearance  of  extending  the 
obligation  to  a  wider  sphere  —  to  cases,  that  is,  in 
which  a  man's  interest  is  opposed  to  his  contract.  But 
it  is  only  an  appearance.  It  is  indeed  true  that  when 
a  sovereign  has  once  been  set  up,  fraud  and  force  cease 
to  pay,  as  a  general  rule,  and  honesty  becomes  the 
best  policy.  But  that  is  more  simply  expressed  with- 
out reference  to  a  contract.  It  merely  means  that  the 
most  selfish  of  mankind  finds  that  it  is  worth  while  to 
have  a  policeman  round  the  corner.  Indeed  the  more 


iv.]  THE   STATE  211 

selfish  he  is  the  greater  may  be  the  convenience.  By 
abandoning  my  supposed  right  to  all  things,  I  get  an 
effectual  right  to  most  things ;  and  that  may  be  called 
a  bargain,  but  it  is  a  bargain  which  I  shall  only  keep, 
and  indeed  can  only  keep,  according  to  Hobbes,  so 
long  as  the  balance  of  profit  is  on  my  side.  That  is, 
it  is  not  a  bargain  at  all. 

The  facts,  however,  remain,  and  Hobbes  manages  to 
state  a  clear  and  coherent  scheme.  His  position  may 
be  compared  to  that  of  the  old  economists.  They  used 
to  maintain  that  in  taking  for  granted  the  selfishness 
of  mankind  they  were  making  a  legitimate  abstraction. 
Men,  it  is  true,  are  not  simply  selfish,  they  have  other 
motives  than  a  love  of  money ;  but  the  love  of  money 
is  so  prominent  an  instinct  in  economic  masses  that  we 
may  consider  it  as  the  sole  force  at  work,  and  so  we 
may  get  a  theory  which  will  be  approximately  true, 
though  requiring  correction  when  applied  to  concrete 
cases.  Hobbes  virtually  considers  the  political  system 
in  so  far  as  it  is  based  upon  selfish  motives  and  is 
worked  by  individual  interests.  No  doubt  such  mo- 
tives are  tolerably  prevalent.  The  obvious  and  most 
assignable  motive  for  obeying  the  law  is  fear  of  the 
hangman ;  and  all  manner  of  selfish  interests  are 
furthered  by  maintaining  a  settled  system  of  govern- 
ment. He  thus  obtains  a  clear  conception  of  one 
important  aspect  of  the  political  order.  It  means  or- 
ganised force.  The  State  is  held  together  by  armies 
which  protect  us  from  invasion,  and  by  the  admini- 
strative system  which  preserves  order  at  home.  These 
are  undeniable  facts  which  it  is  as  well  to  recognise 
clearly,  and  which  are  most  vigorously  set  forth  in 
Hobbes's  Leviathan. 


212  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Certain  limits  to  the  value  of  his  theory  are  equally 
plain.  In  the  Leviathan  Hobbes  says  that  the  "  public 
ministers  "  are  parts  organical  of  the  commonwealth, 
and  compares  the  judges  to  the  "  organs  of  voice,"  the 
executive  to  the  hands,  ambassadors  to  eyes,  and  so 
forth.  The  analogy  between  the  political  and  the  indi- 
vidual organism  is  implied  in  the  whole  theory.  But 
the  Leviathan  is  an  "  artificial "  body,  and  "  artificial ': 
means  mechanical  construction.  The  individual  is  the 
ultimate  unit,  and  though  he  resigns  his  rights  to  the 
sovereign,  it  is  always  for  his  own  personal  advantage. 
The  comparison  to  a  body  suggests  the  modern  phrase 
"the  social  organism,"  but  the  "artificial'1'  indicates 
that  Hobbes  does  not  really  interpret  the  Leviathan  as 
an  organism.  It  is  a  big  machine  or  set  of  atoms  held 
together  by  external  bonds.  Hobbes's  egoism  forces 
him  to  the  doctrine  that  the  particles  gravitate  to- 
gether simply  from  fear — fear  of  the  magistrate  or  fear 
of  your  neighbour.  Sympathy  is  ignored,  and  such 
sentiments  as  patriotism  or  public  spirit  or  philan- 
thropy are  superficial  modifications  of  selfishness, 
implying  a  readiness  to  adopt  certain  precautions  for 
securing  our  own  lives  and  properties.  This  involves 
a  one-sided  view  of  the  conditions  of  social  and  political 
welfare.  It  may  be  fully  admitted  that  organised  force 
is  essential  to  a  civilised  society,  that  it  cannot  exist 
or  develop  without  its  military  and  judicial  bodies,  its 
soldiers  and  its  judges,  its  hangmen,  gaolers,  and  police- 
men, its  whole  protective  apparatus.  An  animal  cannot 
live  without  its  teeth  and  claws.  What  is  overlooked 
is  the  truth  that  other  parts  of  the  system  are  equally 
essential,  and  that  there  is  a. reciprocal  dependence 
indicated  by  the  word  "  organic."  Society  is  held 


iv.]  THE    STATE  213 

together  not  simply  by  the  legal  sanctions,  but  by  all 
the  countless  instincts  and  sympathies  which  bind  men 
together,  and  by  the  spontaneous  associations  which 
have  their  sources  outside  of  the  political  order.  "It 
may  be  granted  to  Hobbes  that  peace  is  an  essential 
condition  of  progress,  and  that  the  sovereign  must  be 
created  to  keep  the  peace.  It  is  equally  true  that  the 
sovereign  derives  his  power  from  other  sources  than 
mutual  "  fear );  or  dread  of  the  "  legal  sanctions." 
Society  could  not  get  on  without  the  policeman ;  but 
the  policeman  could  not  keep  order  by  the  simple  force 
of  his  truncheon.  Force  must  be  "organised,"  but  it 
cannot  be  organised  out  of  simple  egoism  and  fear. 
So  when  Hobbes  defines  law  as  the  command  of  the 
sovereign,  he  is  stating  what  in  a  fully  developed  State 
is  an  undeniable  fact.  The  law  is  the  system  of  rules 
promulgated  and  enforced  by  the  sovereign  power  in 
spite  of  any  conflicting  customs.  Historically  speak- 
ing, laws  are  not  the  less  the  product  of  customs  which 
have  grown  up  spontaneously ;  they  are  the  causes,  not 
the  effects  of  the  sovereign's  authority ;  and  in  the 
last  resort  the  sovereign  power  must  still  rest  upon 
custom ;  that  is,  upon  all  the  complex  motives  from 
which  arises  loyalty  to  the  State,  and  upon  which  its 
vitality  depends. 

Hobbes's  position  was  indeed  inevitable.  The  con- 
ception of  sociology  as  a  science,  in  which  the  political 
order  is  regarded  as  only  part  of  the  whole  social 
system,  had  not  yet  arisen.  That  could  not  happen 
until  historical  methods  of  inquiry  had  begun  to  show 
their  power,  and  the  necessity  of  treating  political 
questions  in  connection  with  the  intellectual  or  the 
industrial  evolution  began  to  be  perceived.  The 


214  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

"  social  contract "  theory  helped  Hobbes  to  pass  over  in 
summary  fashion  the  great  historical  problems  as  to  the 
way  in  which  the  State  has  actually  been  developed ; 
and  therefore  the  State  itself  could  be  regarded  as 
held  together  by  the  purely  political  and  legal  forces. 
When  he  had  deduced  the  sovereign  power  from  the 
principle  of  self-preservation,  he  seemed  to  himself  to 
have  explained  everything.  He  had  got  to  the  one 
force  which  held  the  units  together,  as  gravitation 
holds  together  the  solar  system.  The  relation  between 
subject  and  sovereign  is  the  one  bond  from  which  all 
others  may  be  deduced.  The  thoroughgoing  accept- 
ance of  this  assumption  leads  to  some  of  the  singular 
results  by  which  he  startled  his  contemporaries, 
though  he  announces  them  with  superlative  calmness 
as  demonstrated  truths. 

There  are,  as  he  has  to  admit,  two  sets  of  laws 
which  may  occasionally  conflict  with  the  laws  of 
the  State.  In  the  first  place,  there  is  the  moral  law. 
Hobbes  was  perfectly  well  aware  that  a  king  might  be 
a  fool  or  a  brute.  It  seemed  to  follow  that  laws  might 
be  contrary  to  the  dictates  of  morality.  His  opponents 
could  point  out  to  him  that  some  of  the  Roman  em- 
perors had  been  far  from  model  characters.  Besides 
their  other  weaknesses,  they  had  occasionally  thought 
it  right  to  give  Christians  to  lions.  Again,  the  Chris- 
tian Church  claimed  obedience,  and  Hobbes  was  an 
orthodox  Christian.  What  is  the  subject  to  do  if  his 
sovereign  orders  him  to  break  the  moral  law  or  to 
deny  the  truth  of  religion? 

4.    The  Moral  Law 
Hobbes  does  not   shrink   from   the   logical   result 


iv.]  THE    STATE  215 

of  his  principles.  The  moral  law,  he  holds,  is  the 
Law  of  Nature.  The  Law  of  Nature,  as  we  have 
seen,  means  essentially  the  law  of  self-preserva- 
tion, and  from  that  is  deduced  the  "  virtue '  of 
justice,  from  which  all  other  laws  of  nature  are 
corollaries.  Justice  means  keeping  covenants,  which 
becomes  operative  when  a  "  coercive  power  "  is  consti- 
tuted ;  that  is,  at  the  institution  of  the  social  contract. 
This  contract  therefore  is  at  the  base  of  all  moral  as 
well  as  of  all  political  relations.  It  is  presupposed  in 
all  particular  contracts.  Justice,  the  cardinal  or  rather 
the  sole  virtue,  means  keeping  covenants,  but  also 
keeping  the  primitive  contract  to  which  all  others  owe 
their  binding  force.  It  implies,  therefore,  unconditional 
obedience  to  the  sovereign  who  is  the  social  contract 
incarnate.  The  sovereign  cannot  be  unjust  to  a  sub- 
ject ;  for  every  subject  is  himself  author  of  all  that  the 
sovereign  does.  Laws  are  the  "rules  of  just  and 
unjust ;  nothing  being  reputed  unjust  that  is  not  con- 
trary to  some  law."  "The  Law  of  Nature  and  the 
civil  law  contain  each  other  and  are  of  equal  extent." 
"Justice,  gratitude,  and  other  moral  virtues'5  are 
merely  "  qualities  that  dispose  men  to  peace  and 
obedience"  until  the  commonwealth  is  instituted. 
Then  they  become  laws,  "  for  it  is  the  sovereign  power 
that  obliges  men  to  obey  them."  Thus  the  Law  of 
Nature  is  part  of  the  civil  law,  and  "  reciprocally  the 
civil  law  is  part  of  the  dictates  of  nature." 

Nobody,  I  believe,  ever  followed  Hobbes  in  this 
audacious  identification  of  law  and  morality.  I  must 
try  to  make  some  apology  for  a  most  estimable  old 
gentleman  misled  by  an  excessive  passion  for  logic. 
In  the  first  place,  it  may  be  held  that,  whatever  be  the 


216  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

ultimate  meaning  of  morality,  the  actual  morality  of  a 
race  is  evolved  in  constant  correlation  with  its  social 
organisation.     Hobbes,  who  substituted  the  social  con- 
tract  for   this   process,  and  /regarded  sovereignty  as 
the  sole  bond  of  union,  could  only  approximate  to  this 
doctrine  by  making  moral  obligations  a  product  of  the 
sovereign  will.     It  would  be  outrageous,  no  doubt,  to 
suppose  that  a  sovereign  could  make  the  moral  law  at 
his  pleasure,  so  that  lying  might  become  a  virtue  or 
gratitude  a  vice  if  the  lawgiver  chose  to  alter  the  law. 
That  is  not  Hobbes's  meaning. !  Honesty,  gratitude,  and 
the  like  are,  we  see,  useful  qualities  and  parts  of  the 
Law  of  Nature  as  tending  to  self-preservation.     The 
sovereign  of  course  cannot  alter  that  fact. ,'/  What  he 
can  do  is  to  make  them  obligatory  by  establishing  the 
state  of  security  which  makes  their  exercise  possible  or 
prudent  for  the  individual.  /  In  the  "  state  of  nature ': 
the  conduct  would  be  self -destructive  which,  when  the 
commonwealth  is  formed,   becomes   self-preservative. 
But,  we  may  ask,  will  the  power  thus  constituted  aim 
at  the  end  for  which  it  was  instituted  ?     May  not  the 
sovereign  do  wrong  ?     May  he  not  be  a  brutal  tyrant, 
or  lay  down  laws  which  are  immoral,  because  incon- 
sistent with  the  welfare  of  the  people  ?     Is  it  in  that 
case   our   duty  to   obey   them  ?     Must  we  submit  to 
oppression    or    enslave   our   neighbours   because  the 
sovereign,  whether  king  or  parliament,  commands  it  ? 
Hobbes  admits  the  possibility.     "  They  that  have  the 
sovereign  power  may  commit  iniquity,  but  not  injustice 
or  injury  in  the  proper   signification.'7     That  is,  the 
sovereign's  immorality  gives  no  right  to  the  subject  to 
disobey  or  even  to  protest.     The  reason   is  that  the 
only  alternative  is  anarchy.     Bad  laws  are  better  than 


iv.]  THE   STATE  217 

no  laws.  "  Good,"  as  we  have  seen,  means  what  a  man 
desires  and  evil  what  he  eschews.  "  One  counts  that 
good  which  another  counts  evil ;  and  the  same  man  what 
now  he  esteemed  for  good,  he  immediately  after  looks 
on  as  evil ;  and  the  same  thing  which  he  calls  good  in 
himself  he  terms  evil  in  another."  There  is  no  such 
thing  as  absolute  good.  Hence  it  is  impossible  to 
make  a  common  rule  from  the  tastes  of  "  particular  " 
men.  We  have  to  consider  what  is  reasonable ;  but 
"there  are  no  other  reasons  in  being  but  those  of  par- 
ticular men  and  that  of  the  city ;  it  follows  that  the 
city  is  to  determine  what  with  reason  is  culpable." 
We  are  bound  to  obey  the  laws  before  we  know  what 
the  laws  are;  for  the  State  must  precede  the  law. 
Therefore  "  no  civil  law  whatever  can  be  against  the 
Law  of  Nature."  The  Law  of  Nature  may  forbid  theft 
and  adultery ;  but  till  we  have  civil  laws  we  do  not 
know  what  theft  and  adultery  are.  When  the  Spar- 
tans permitted  their  youth  to  take  other  men's  goods, 
the  taking  was  not  theft.  In  other  words,  all  law 
becomes  positive  law,  for  the  Law  of  Nature  only 
orders  us  to  obey  the  law  of  the  sovereign.  It  has 
been  said  that  "  whatsoever  a  man  does  against  his 
conscience  is  sin."  That  is  true  in  the  "  state  of 
nature,"  where  a  man  has  no  rule  but  his  own  reason. 
"  It  is  not  so  with  him  that  lives  in  a  commonwealth, 
because  the  law  is  the  public  conscience  by  which  he 
hath  already  undertaken  to  be  guided."  Otherwise 
nobody  would  obey  further  than  it  seemed  good  in  his 
own  eyes. 

The  subject,  then,  hands  over  the  whole  responsi- 
bility to  the  sovereign.  Then  "  it  is  in  the  laws  of  a 
commonwealth  as  it  is  in  the  laws  of  gaming;  whatso- 


,w: 

V; 

\j£-^ 
**     of        &J 


218  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

ever  the  gamesters  all  agree  on  is  injustice  to  none  of 
them."  /Are  then  the  laws  as  arbitrary  as  the  laws  of 
a  game  ?  To  that  Hobbes  has  his  answer :  "  The  safety 
of  the  people  is  the  supreme  law."  The  sovereign  is 
"  obliged  by  the  Law  of  Nature  "  to  procure  this  end, 
"  and  to  render  an  account  thereof  to  God  and  to  none 
but  Him."  Remembering  the  peculiarity  of  Hobbes's 
theology,  it  may  seem  that  this  responsibility  is  per- 
haps illusory.  It  is  more  to  his  purpose  that,  as  he 
puts  it,  "  the  good  of  the  sovereign  and  people  cannot 
be  separated."  "  It  is  a  weak  sovereign  that  has  weak 
subjects,  and  a  weak  people  whose  sovereign  wanteth 
power  to  rule  them  at  his  will."  It  is  clearly  to  the 
interest  of  the  sovereign,  as  it  is  also  his  duty,  to  main- 
tain order.  But  to  maintain  order  is,  according  to 
Hobbes,  to  enforce  morality.  The  sovereign  has  to 
instruct  his  people  in  the  "  fundamental  rights  "  of  his  ' 
office.  To  do  so  is  "  not  only  his  duty,  but  his  benefit 
also,  and  security  against  the  danger  that  may  arise  to 
himself  in  his  natural  person  from  rebellion."  He  pro- 
ceeds in  his  quaint  fashion  to  point  out  that  this  duty 
of  instructing  the  people  is  the  duty  of  impressing 
upon  them  the  Ten  Commandments.  Since  kings  are 
mortal  gods,  the  commandments  of  the  first  table  are 
applicable  to  them  as  well  as  to  the  Supreme  Being. 
Clearly  a  man  who  proves  that  kings  not  only  should 
but  naturally  will  adopt  the  Ten  Commandments  is 
preaching  a  sound  morality. 

It  is  necessary,  however,  to  remember  Hobbes's 
general  ethical  conception.  Every  man  acts  simply 
for  his  own  good.  Every  man,  again,  interprets 
"  good  "  as  that  which  pleases  him.  Order  can  only  be 
established  when  every  man  sees  that  he  will  get  more 


iv.]  THE   STATE  219 

good  for  himself  by  submitting  to  a  common  authority. 
When  that  is  securely  established,  the  individual  will 
be  repaid  for  sacrificing  that  right  to  everything 
which  he  could  not  enforce.  But  when  that  is  done, 
the  moral  law  is  made  supreme.  For  morality,  accord- 
ing to  Hobbes,  is  summed  up  in  justice ;  that  is,  in 
observing  the  general  contract  according  to  which  the 
distribution  of  good  things  is  regulated  and  men  are 
obliged  to  keep  their  particular  contracts.  Equality 
before  the  law  and  equality  of  taxation  are  also  implied, 
for  inequality  leads  to  discontent.  But  in  other 
respects  every  man  may,  and  of  course  will  be  guided 
by  his  own  conceptions  of  "good."  As  I  have  said 
before,/ Hobbes  is  not  in  favour  of  extending  the 
sphere  of  legislation.  Laws  are  "like  hedges,"  set 
"  not  to  stop  travellers  but  to  keep  them  in  their  way. 
And  therefore  a  law  which  is  not  needful,  having  not 
the  true  end  of  law,  is  not  good."  "  Unnecessary 
laws  are  not  good  laws,  but  traps  for  money ;  which, 
where  the  right  of  sovereign  power  is  acknowledged, 
are  superfluous ;  and  where  it  is  not  acknowledged, 
insufficient  to  defend  the  people." 

This,  it  seems,  is  the  essential  meaning  of  Hobbes's 
identification  of  law  and  morality.  They  are,  accord- 
ing to  him,  different  aspects  of  the  virtue  which  he 
calls  justice.  That  means  that  a  man  acts  morally  so 
far  as  he  pursues  his  own  ends  without  harming  his 
neighbour;  and  legally,  so  far  as  he  obeys  the  sove- 
reign who  enforces  the  security  without  which  it  is 
not  a  man's  interest  to  act  morally.  No  doubt  this  is 
a  totally  inadequate  view  of  morality.  It  is  the  legal 
or  purely  external  conception  which  supposes  that  the 
moral,  like  the  positive  law,  is  satisfied  by  obeying 


220  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

certain  "  sanctions  "  which  make  bad  conduct  unprofit- 
able. But  it  does  not  imply  that  the  moral  law  is 
"arbitrary"  or  made  at  will  by  the  sovereign.  It  is 
the  law  of  "  self-preservation  "  regarded  from  a  purely 
egoistic  point  of  view. 


5.    TJie  Spiritual  Power 

Hobbes's  theory  may  lead  to  some  pretty  problems 
in  casuistry.  How  far  should  a  man's  duty  to  the 
state  override  the  dictates  of  his  conscience  ?  May  a 
soldier  refuse  to  serve  in  a  war  that  he  thinks  unjust  ? 
Or  a  Quaker  refuse  to  fight  at  all  ?  May  a  man  refuse 
to  pay  taxes  if  he  disapproves  of  the  purpose  for 
which  they  are  raised  ?  To  admit  such  liberty  un- 
reservedly is  to  approve  of  anarchy,  and  upon  that 
ground  some  people  become  anarchists.  The  problem, 
however,  does  not  often  present  itself  in  practice. 
Most  laws  are  sufficiently  in  conformity  with  the 
average  morality  of  the  people  to  excite  no  protest. 
But  another  question  was  far  more  pressing,  and  to 
Hobbes  seemed  to  be  the  really  critical  question  of 
the  day.  What  is  to  be  done  when  the  subject's 
religious  convictions  clash  with  his  obligations  to  the 
State  ?  To  that  problem  Hobbes  gave  an  answer  in 
his  first  treatise,  which  was  expanded  in  the  De  Cive, 
and  given  at  great  length  and  with  many  singular 
developments  in  the  Leviathan. 

His  essential  position  is  simple  enough :  the  sove- 
reign has  to  keep  the  peace.  Now  men's  "  actions 
proceed  from  their  opinions,"  and  therefore  opinions 
must  be  governed  in  order  to  govern  action,  and 
governed  in  the  interests  of  peace.  He  agrees 


iv.]  THE   STATE  221 

that  in  speculation  "  nothing  ought  to  be  regarded 
but  the  truth."  True  opinion,  however,  cannot  be 
"  repugnant  to  peace."  "  Yet  the  most  sudden  and 
rough  bursting  in  of  a  new  truth,  that  can  be,  does 
never  break  the  peace  but  only  sometimes  awake  the 
war ; ';  that  is,  where  error  is  already  prevalent 
and  people  are  ready  to  fight  for  it.  It  follows  that 
the  suppression  of  an  opinion  "  repugnant  to  peace," 
must  also  be  the  suppression  of  error.  He  limits  the 
suppression,  however,  to  the  public  teaching,  through 
books  or  otherwise,  of  objectionable  opinions,  for  he 
also  holds  that  a  man's  private  beliefs  cannot  be  deter- 
mined by  force.  The  sovereign  is  therefore  bound 
to  forbid  the  open  propagation  of  opinions  by  which 
his  authority  is  subverted.  The  diseases  which  bring 
about  the  "  dissolution  of  commonwealths  "  are  seditious 
opinions.  Besides  the  opinion  that  every  private  man 
is  to  judge  of  good  and  evil,  there  is  the  opinion 
that  a  man  may  claim  supernatural  inspiration:  a 
pernicious  doctrine  which  in  this  part  of  the  world 
has  been  turned  to  account  by  "unlearned  divines," 
sufficiently  prevalent  in  the  fanatical  sects  of  the 
commonwealth. 

But  a  still  more  vital  power  is  represented  by  the 
claims  of  the  papacy.  This,  in  fact,  means  the  cardinal 
error  of  a  divided  sovereignty.  It  is  a  setting  up  of 
"supremacy  against  sovereignty;  canons  against  laws, 
and  a  ghostly  authority  against  the  civil."  "  Now  see- 
ing it  is  manifest  that  the  civil  power  and  the  power 
of  the  commonwealth  is  the  same  thing,  and  that 
supremacy  and  the  power  of  making  canons  .  .  .  im- 
plieth  a  commonwealth,  it  followeth  that  where  one 
is  sovereign,  another  supreme  —  where  one  can  make 


222  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

laws  and  another  make  canons  —  there  must  needs  be 
two  commonwealths  of  one  and  the  same  subjects, 
which  is  a  kingdom  divided  against  itself  and  cannot 
stand."  The  "ghostly  power  challengeth  the  right 
to  declare  what  is  sin/7  and  therefore  the  right  to 
declare  what  is  law,  for  sin  is  "  nothing  but  the  trans- 
gression of  the  law."  As  the  civil  power  also  declares 
what  is  law,  it  follows  either  that  every  subject  must 
obey  two  masters,  or  that  one  of  the  two  powers 
must  be  subordinate  to  the  other.  The  civil  authority 
has  the  advantage  of  being  "  more  visible " ;  but  the 
spiritual,  though  it  deals  in  unintelligible  doctrines, 
yet,  "because  the  fear  of  darkness  and  ghosts  is 
greater  than  other  fears,  cannot  want  a  party  sufficient 
to  trouble  and  sometimes  to  destroy  a  commonwealth." 
The  spiritual  power,  indeed,  has  an  advantage,  "for 
every  man"  (as  he  says  in  the  De  Give),  "if  he  be 
in  his  wits,  will  in  all  things  yield  that  man  an 
absolute  obedience,  by  virtue  of  whose  sentence  he 
believes  himself  to  be  either  saved  or  damned." 
Church  or  State,  that  is,  must  be  supreme,  or  there 
will  be  a  fatal  disease  which  he  quaintly  compares  to 
the  epilepsy,  a  "  wind  in  the  head,"  which  makes  men 
fall  into  fire  or  water.  When  the  spiritual  power 
moves  the  subject  "by  the  terror  of  punishment  and 
hope  of  reward r  of  this  supernatural  kind,  "and  by 
strange  and  hard  words  suffocates  their  understanding, 
it  must  needs  thereby  distract  the  people,  and  either 
overwhelm  the  commonwealth  by  oppression  or  cast  it 
into  the  fire  of  a  civil  war."  Which  then  is  to  be 
supreme  ?  A  church,  like  a  state,  must  be  an  organised 
body  and  have  a  sovereign  before  it  can  be  said  to 
"will"  or  "command."  He  defines  it  therefore  as  a 


iv.]  THE   STATE  223 

"  company  of  men  professing  Christian  religion  united 
in  the  person  of  one  sovereign,  at  whose  command 
they  ought  to  assemble,  and  without  whose  authority 
they  ought  not  to  assemble.7'  Now,  in  all  common- 
wealths,  an  assembly  in  order  to  be  lawful  must  have 
the  warrant  of  the  civil  sovereign.  There  is  no  power 
on  earth  to  which  all  commonwealths  are  subject,  and 
the  Christians  in  each  State  are  subject  to  its  sovereign 
and  cannot  be  subject  to  any  other  power.  Therefore 
a  church  is  the  same  thing  with  the  civil  common- 
wealth, which  is  "  called  a  civil  state,  for  that  the 
subjects  of  it  are  men,  and  a  church  for  that  the 
subjects  thereof  are  Christians."  "Temporal'1  and 
"spiritual"  are  "two  words  brought  into  the  world 
to  make  men  see  double  and  mistake  their  lawful 
sovereign."  Unless  there  is  one  governor  there  will 
be  civil  war  between  Church  and  State  —  "  between 
the  sword  of  justice  and  the  shield  of  faith — and,  which 
is  more,  in  every  Christian  man's  own  breast  between 
the  Christian  and  the  man." 

The  Church,  in  short,  as  a  law-making  or  governing 
body  must  be  fused  with  the  State.  Otherwise  we 
have  the  fatal  splitting  of  sovereignty.  An  antagonist 
might  have  replied  that  the  unity  might  be  equally 
secured  by  subordinating  the  State  to  the  Church. 
An  absolute  theocracy,  such  as  corresponded  to  the 
extremest  claims  of  the  papacy,  would  have  satisfied 
the  condition  as  fully  as  the  secular  sovereignty.  To 
this  Hobbes  replies  upon  the  historical  ground.  He 
denies  that  the  Church  of  Rome,  or  indeed  that  the 
spiritual  power  from  the  beginning  of  the  world,  can 
make  out  any  title  to  the  sovereign  power.  Half  of 
the  Leviathan,  namely  the  third  part  ("  Of  a  Christian 


224  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

Commonwealth ")  and  the  fourth  ("  Of  the  Kingdom 
of  Darkness  "),  is  devoted  to  this  argument. 

It  is  a  most  singular  performance.  Hobbes  has  to 
argue  from  the  Bible,  and  quotes  texts  as  confidently 
as  any  contemporary  divine.  He  protests,  indeed, 
with  an  air  of  perfect  candour,  that  he  has  only  taken 
the  plainest  sense  and  that  which  is  "  agreeable  to  the 
harmony  and  scope  of  the  whole  Bible."  But  his 
exegesis  brings  out  results  which  nobody  before  or 
since  has  ever  deduced  from  the  same  authority.  We 
may  wonder  whether  he  is  sincere  or  laughing  in 
his  sleeve;  whether,  perhaps,  he  means  simply  an 
argument  ad  hominem;  or  a  tacit  suggestion  that  any 
conclusions  you  please  can  be  extorted  from  the 
documents  whose  authority  he  is  bound  to  admit. 
Our  confidence  is  not  increased  by  his  apology  for  his 
paradoxes.  He  admits  that  one  doctrine,  which  he 
proves,  will  appear  to  most  men  a  novelty.  "  I  do  but 
propound  it,"  he  says,  l<  maintaining  nothing  in  this  or 
any  other  paradox  of  religion,  but  attending  the  end 
of  that  dispute  of  the  sword  concerning  the  authority, 
not  yet  amongst  my  countrymen  decided,  by  which  all 
sorts  of  doctrine  are  to  be  approved  or  rejected." 
Anyhow  the  results  are  too  grotesque  to  be  given  at 
length,  or  to  be  quite  passed  over. 

His  contention  is  essentially  that  there  never  was 
a  divinely  instituted  spiritual  authority  independent 
of  the  civil  authority.  The  civil  and  ecclesiastical 
power,  for  example,  were  united  in  Abraham,  after- 
wards in  Moses,  and  then  in  the  high  priests.  "  Who- 
ever had  the  sovereignty  of  the  commonwealth  among 
the  Jews,  the  same  had  also  the  supreme  authority  in 
the  matter  of  God's  external  worship,"  though  the 


iv.]  THE   STATE  225 

Jews  got  into  many  calamities  from  not  properly 
understanding  the  rights  of  their  rulers.  The  old 
dispensation,  it  might  be  supposed,  was  superseded 
by  the  Christian  Church,  and  its  rulers  would  repre- 
sent Christ  on  earth.  But  "  the  Kingdom  of  Christ ' 
was  not  of  this  world.  That,  according  to  Hobbes, 
means  that  it  will  not  be  established  until  a  new 
world  begins  upon  "  the  general  resurrection."  Then 
Christ  will  become  a  King  in  the  literal  sense.  The 
good  will  come  to  life  in  their  old  bodies  (for  there 
is  no  such  thing  as  a  separate  soul)  and  live  eternally. 
They  will  not  marry  or  be  given  in  marriage,  for 
otherwise  the  earth  would  obviously  not  be  big  enough 
to  hold  the  resulting  population.  There  will  be  no 
death  vacancies.  The  wicked  will  also  come  to  life 
in  order  to  receive  condign  punishment.  They  will 
suffer  "  the  second  death,"  which  cannot,  as  he  thinks, 
mean  eternal  life  in  torture,  but  simple  extinction. 
As  they  will  die,  they  may  propagate ;  and  therefore 
hell  may  be  eternal  in  the  sense  that  there  will  always 
be  a  supply  of  the  wicked  to  be  punished,  though 
every  individual  will  come  to  an  end.  This  amazing 
theory  is  meant  to  show  that  since  Christ's  kingdom 
is  not  to  become  a  reality  until  the  resurrection,  the 
Church  is,  for  the  time  being,  not  a  kingdom  at  all 
but  a  mere  voluntary  association.  The  apostles  and 
their  successors  could  only  persuade,  not  command, 
and  had  no  coercive  powers.  Excommunication 
could  only  mean  amicable  separation,  not  the  in- 
fliction of  a  penalty.  The  Church  did  not  acquire 
legal  authority  until  it  was  invested  with  power  by 
the  emperor. 

These  queer  speculations  are  connected  with  a  more 
Q 


226  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

interesting  set  of  arguments.  Hobbes  wishes  to  meet 
the  claims  of  the  Church  to  supernatural  authority. 
He  cannot  deny  —  explicitly  at  any  rate  —  that  Moses 
and  the  prophets  were  divinely  inspired.  What  he  can 
do  is  to  argue  that  their  inspiration  does  not  transmit 
supernatural  authority  to  their  descendants.  Moses 
himself  knew  that  he  was  speaking  to  Jehovah.  But 
in  what  way  Jehovah  spoke  to  him  is  "  not  intelligible." 
The  Jews  could  only  know  that  Moses  told  them  that 
he  was  so  speaking,  and  that  makes  a  vital  difference. 
When  a  prophet  says  that  God  has  spoken  to  him  in 
a  dream,  that  is  only  to  say  he  "  dreamed  that  God 
spoke  to  him,  which  is  not  of  force  to  win  belief  from 
any  man  that  knows  that  dreams  are  for  the  most 
part  natural."  To  say  that  a  man  speaks  by  "  super- 
natural inspiration  is  to  say  he  finds  an  ardent  desire 
to  speak  in  some  strong  opinion  of  himself,  for  which 
he  can  allege  no  natural  and  sufficient  reason.  So  that, 
though  God  Almighty  can  speak  to  a  man  by  dreams, 
visions,  voice,  and  inspiration,  yet  he  obliges  no  man 
to  believe  he  hath  so  done  to  him  that  pretends  it, 
who,  being  a  man,  may  err,  and  which  is  more,  may 
lie."  As  miracles  have  ceased,  we  can  now  only  appeal 
to  the  Holy  Scriptures.  What,  then,  is  the  authority 
of  the  Scriptures  ?  Hobbes  goes  through  many  of  the 
passages,  which  have  been  mentioned  by  later  critics, 
to  show  that  the  books  ascribed  to  Moses  and  others 
were  written  after  the  time  of  the  supposed  authors. 
The  Psalter  must  have  been  put  into  its  present  form 
after  the  captivity  as  some  of  the  psalms  refer  to  it. 
The  authority,  of  the  Old  Testament  in  general  can 
only  be  traced  to  the  time  of  Esdras,  who  discovered 
the  books  when  they  were  lost;  and  the  canon  of 


iv.]  THE   STATE  227 

the  New  Testament  cannot  be  proved  to  have  been 
authoritative  before  the  Council  of  Laodicea  in  the 
year  364  A.D.  Hobbes,  indeed,  believes  that  the  New 
Testament  books  are  genuine,  for  a  characteristic 
reason :  The  doctors  of  the  Church  had  claimed 
supreme  power  by  the  time  of  the  Council  and 
thought  pious  frauds  commendable.  If  they  had 
altered  the  books  "  they  would  surely  have  made 
them  more  favourable  to  their  power  over  Christian 
princes  .  .  .  than  they  are."  Why,  then,  do  we  believe 
the  Scriptures  to  be  the  Word  of  God  ?  Everybody, 
he  says,  admits  the  fact  of  inspiration,  but  no  one 
can  know  it  except  "  those  to  whom  God  him- 
self hath  revealed  it  superuaturally."  Men  believe, 
though  they  do  not  know,  for  reasons  so  various 
that  no  general  account  of  them  can  be  given.  But 
"  the  question  truly  stated  is,  by  what  authority  they 
(the  Scriptures)  are  made  law."  The  answer  is 
obvious.  They  must  be  imposed  by  a  sovereign 
authority ;  and,  if  so,  either  by  sovereigns  each 
absolute  in  his  own  territory,  or  by  the  "  Vicar  of 
Christ r  as  sovereign  of  the  universal  Church,  who 
must  then  have  the  power  of  judging,  deposing,  or 
putting  to  death  the  subordinate  sovereigns.  Mean- 
while, every  man  is  "  bound  to  make  use  of  his 
natural  reason  "  to  test  the  claims  of  a  prophet.  It 
is  clear  that  a  great  many  prophets  are  not  to 
be  trusted.  When  Ahab  consulted  four  hundred 
prophets,  all  but  one  were  impostors,  "  and  a  little 
before  the  time  of  the  captivity  the  prophets  were 
generally  liars  (see  Jeremiah  xiv.  14)."  We  must 
judge  them  then  by  their  conformity  to  the  estab- 
lished authority.  When  Christians  do  not  take  their 


228  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

own  sovereign  for  God's  prophet,  they  must  take 
their  own  dreams  or  obey  "  some  strange  prince,"  or 
be  bewitched  into  rebellion  and  the  "  chaos  of  violence 
and  civil  war"  by  some  fellow-subject. 

Hobbes  proceeds  to  treat  of  miracles.  We  take 
an  event  to  be  miraculous  when  we  do  not  perceive 
its  cause.  The  first  rainbow  "  was  a  miracle  because 
the  first,"  and  consequently  strange.  A  rainbow  is 
not  a  miracle  now,  because  it  is  no  longer  strange, 
even  to  those  who  do  not  know  the  cause.  That 
may  be  a  miracle  to  one  man  which  is  not  so  to 
another.  Before  astronomy  became  a  science,  a  man 
who  predicted  an  eclipse  would  pass  for  a  prophet. 
Juggling,  ventriloquism,  and  thaumaturgy  are  com- 
mon, and  "  there  is  nothing  how  impossible  soever  to 
be  done  that  is  impossible  to  be  believed."  When  we 
hear  of  a  miracle,  we  must  therefore  consult  the 
lawful  head  of  the  Church  how  far  we  are  to  give 
credit  to  the  story.  "A  private  man  has  always 
the  liberty,  because  thought  is  free,  to  believe  or 
not  believe  in  his  heart  those  acts  that  have  been 
given  out  for  miracles,"  and  he  should  consider  who 
is  likely  to  profit  by  them.  "  But  when  it  comes 
to  the  confession  of  that  faith,  the  private  reason 
must  submit  to  the  public,  that  is  to  say,  to  God's 
lieutenant." 

Hobbes  was  thus  suggesting  doubts  as  to  the 
evidences  of  the  established  creeds,  doubts  which 
were  to  bear  fruit  in  a  later  generation.  Spinoza, 
in  the  Tractatus  Theologico-Foliticus,  treated  the  ques- 
tions on  wider  grounds  and  "went  a  bar';  beyond 
what  Hobbes  has  dared  to  say.  No  active  con- 
troversy, however,  arose  till  a  later  period.  Hobbes's 


iv.]  THE   STATE  229 

argument,  we  may  notice,  has  a  resemblance  to 
that  which  Hume  made  famous.  Both  of  them 
argue,  not  that  miracles  are  impossible,  but  that  the 
proof  of  a  miracle  is  always  insufficient.  Hobbes 
has  to  assert  that  the  events  recorded  in  the  Scrip- 
tures really  happened,  but  endeavours  to  show  that 
there  is  no  proof  that  they  happened.  We  must 
believe  on  authority,  and,  moreover,  on  the  authority 
of  the  Church.  Only  by  authority  we  do  not  mean 
the  intellectual  authority  of  competent  inquirers,  but 
the  legal  authority  of  the  sovereign.  Rather,  we  may 
believe  what  we  like,  but  we  may  only  profess  the 
belief  which  the  law  allows  us  to  profess. 

We  have  still  to  see  why  he  rejects  the  alternative 
of  the  supremacy  of  the  Church.  The  existing  com- 
monwealths are  independent  of  each  other,  and  there- 
fore not  subject  in  fact  to  any  central  authority ;  but 
it  may  still  be  urged  that  they  ought  to  be  subject  to 
this.  To  this  he  replies  partly  by  the  familiar  Pro- 
testant arguments  from  texts,  and  maintains  that 
Bellarmine's  interpretations  of  "feed  my  sheep,"  and 
so  forth,  are  erroneous.  But  the  main  answer  is  given 
in  the  last  book  upon  "  The  Kingdom  of  Darkness." 
There  he  takes  up  the  position  which  was  already 
assumed  in  his  account  of  the  natural  history  of  re- 
ligion. The  gods  of  the  heathen  are,  as  we  have 
seen,  mere  "  phantasms  "  —  dreams  mistaken  for  reality 
and  so  forth.  The  Church  of  Rome  adopted  the  same 
methods.  By  misinterpreting  Scripture  the  priests 
made  people  believe  in  devils  and  exorcism,  in 
purgatory  and  the  efficiency  of  sacraments,  and  other 
doctrines  calculated  to  increase  their  power  and  give 
them  authority  over  the  secular  rulers.  They  adopted 


230  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

many  ceremonies  and  superstitions  from  the  Gentiles, 
and  they  introduced  the  vain  and  erroneous  philosophy 
of  Aristotle  to  perplex  men's  minds.  The  argument 
ends  by  a  quaint  comparison  between  the  papacy  and 
the  "  kingdom  of  fairies."  The  whole  "  hierarchy  "  has 
been  built  up  like  the  "  old  wives'  fables  in  England 
concerning  ghosts  and  spirits  and  the  feats  they  play 
in  the  night."  It  is  needless  to  go  into  the  details ; 
but  I  may  quote  the  striking  phrase  which  sums  up  his 
theory.  "  If  a  man  consider  the  original  of  this  great 
ecclesiastical  dominion,  he  will  easily  perceive  that 
the  papacy  is  no  other  than  the  ghost  of  the  deceased 
Roman  empire  sitting  crowned  upon  the  grave 
thereof."  "  The  Eoman  Church,"  says  a  great  living 
authority,  "  in  this  way  privily  pushed  itself  into  the 
place  of  the  Roman  world-empire  of  which  it  is  the 
historical  continuation." 1  A  comparison  of  the  phrases 
may  illustrate  Hobbes's  vigorous  grasp  of  thought  as 
well  as  command  of  words. 

His  ascription  of  sovereignty  in  religious  matters  to 
the  civil  authority  was  startling  enough  and  led  him. 
into  some  difficulties.  What,  for  example,  are  we  to 
say  of  the  Christian  martyrs  ?  They  were  clearly 
rebels  and  yet  have  been  generally  praised  for  their 
conduct.  Hobbes  has  to  "  distinguish."  To  be  a  true 
martyr,  a  man  must  have  "  received  a  calling  to 
preach."  He  must,  moreover,  have  seen  the  facts  to 
which  he  testifies.  "  If  he  testifies  to  the  resurrection, 
he  must  have  conversed  with  Christ  before  his  death 
and  seen  him  after  he  was  risen.  Otherwise  he  can 
only  be  a  "  martyr  "  (that  is,  a  witness)  to  other  men's 

1  Harnack's  What  is  Christianity?  p.  252. 


iv.]  THE   STATE  231 

testimony.  Moreover,  there  is  only  one  article  for 
which  a  man  ought  to  die,  namely,  that  "  Jesus  is  the 
Christ."  We  are  not  to  die  for  every  private  tenet  of 
our  own  or  for  tenets  which  suit  the  clergy.  Naainan 
set  a  very  convenient  precedent,  and  if,  like  him,  we 
obey  our  sovereign  in  using  words  which  do  not  express 
our  thoughts,  the  action  is  not  ours  but  our  sovereign's. 
To  resist  an  infidel  sovereign  is  to  "  sin  against  the 
laws  of  God  (for  such  are  the  laws  of  nature)  and  the 
counsel  of  the  apostles  "  (i.e.  to  obey  princes).  If  we 
do  not  take  Naamaii's  view,  we  must  expect  our 
reward  in  heaven.  "  But,"  he  asks,  "  what  infidel 
king  is  so  unreasonable  as,  knowing  he  has  a  subject 
that  waiteth  for  the  second  coming  of  Christ  after  the 
present  world  shall  be  burnt,  and  intendeth  then  to 
obey  him  (which  is  the  intent  of  believing  that  Jesus  is 
the  Christ),  and  in  the  meantime  thinketh  himself 
bound  to  obey  the  laws  of  that  infidel  king  (which  all 
Christians  are  obliged  in  conscience  to  do),  to  put  to 
death  or  persecute  such  a  subject?'  Certainly  if  all 
that  is  meant  by  belief  in  Christ  is  an  intention  of 
obeying  him  as  a  king  after  the  general  resurrection, 
the  infidel  king  would  be  very  unreasonable.  They 
sometimes  are. 

Hobbes  sums  up  his  belief  in  one  phrase.  "  Re- 
ligion," he  says  in  dedicating  his  Seven  Problems  to 
Charles  II.,  "  is  not  philosophy  but  law."  We  have 
already  seen  what  is  the  view  which  he  takes  in  his 
natural  history  of  religion.  Religion  is  the  "  fear  of 
power  invisible."  That  is  the  essential  meaning  of  the 
instinct,  and  legislators  have  taken  advantage  of  it  to 
strengthen  their  own  authority  and  to  keep  the  peace. 
Whether  the  objects  of  worship  be  real  or  "  phantasms," 


232  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

religion  is  useful  just  so  far  as  it  promotes  that  end. 
We  know  nothing  of  God  except  His  power ;  and  it  is 
upon  His  power  that  His  authority  is  founded.  All 
the  other  attributes  ascribed  to  him  "  are  not  to  declare 
what  He  is/'  but  how  much  we  honour  Him.  "  The  end 
of  worship  among  men  is  power."  The  worship  of 
God  is  directed  by  "  those  rules  of  honour  that  reason 
dictateth  to  be  done  by  the  weak  to  the  more  potent 
men  in  hope  of  benefit,"  or  for  fear  of  damage,  or 
thankfulness  for  good  received.  Prayer  and  thanks 
are  simply  an  acknowledgment  of  God's  power. 
Rational  worship  "argues  a  fear  of  Him,  and  fear 
is  a  confession  of  His  power."  I  will  not  ask 
whether  Hobbes's  theological  conceptions  would 
really  justify  even  this  account  of  religion.  It 
comes  apparently  to  this,  that  religion  is  a  system  of 
beliefs  and  observances  imposed  by  the  sovereign  in 
order  to  give  force  to  the  "  Law  of  Nature,"  that  is,  the 
law  of  self-preservation  and  the  obligation  of  the  social 
contract.  Modern  thinkers  have  given  a  good  many 
definitions  of  religion ;  but  this  I  fancy  is  not  among 
them. 

Hobbes's  purpose  is  clear  enough.  The  Church,  as  he 
holds,  is  an  organised  body  which  has  taken  advantage 
of  phantasms  and  dreams  to  claim  supernatural  powers 
and  to  forge  a  system  of  spiritual  weapons  capable  of 
encountering  the  secular  weapons  of  the  sovereign. 
Then  it  has  elaborated  the  sham  philosophy  of  the 
schoolmen,  the  empusa  which  strangles  thought  by 
words  and  enables  it  to  bewilder  men  by  mysterious 
dogmas  which  are  really  nonsense.  In  attacking  the 
/  Church,  therefore,  he  is  defending  the  cause  of  enlight- 
enment against  a  systematic  obscurantism.  He  traces 


w.]  THE   STATE  233 

the  growth  of  the  spiritual  power  through  three  stages : 
first  the  claim  of  priests  to  make  belief  obligatory 
instead  of  free ;  secondly,  the  concentration  of  this 
power  in  the  hands  of  bishops ;  and  thirdly,  absorption 
of  the  episcopal  in  the  papal  power.  Queen  Elizabeth 
got  rid  of  the  pope ;  the  Presbyterians  of  the  bishops  ; 
and  the  Presbyterians  have  now  lost  their  power,  so 
that  "we  are  reduced  to  the  independency  of  the 
primitive  Christians,"  every  man  believing  what  he 
pleases.  This,  he  says,  "is  perhaps  the  best,"  first, 
because  there  ought  to  be  no  power  "over  the  con- 
sciences of  men,  but  of  the  Word  itself,  working  faith 
in  every  man ; "  and  secondly,  because  it  is  unreasonable 
to  ask  a  man  to  accept  the  reasons  of  others,  "  which 
is  little  better  than  to  venture  his  salvation  at  cross 
and  pile."  Priests  ought  to  know  that  power  is  pre- 
served by  the  same  virtues  by  which  it  is  acquired  — 
"that  is  to  say,  by  wisdom,  humility,  clearness  of 
doctrine,  and  sincerity  of  conversation;  and  not  by 
suppression  of  the  natural  sciences  and  of  the  morality 
of  natural  reason ;  nor  by  obscure  language ;  nor  by 
arrogating  to  themselves  more  knowledge  than  they 
make  appear ;  nor  by  pious  frauds ;  "  nor  by  other  faults 
which  tend  to  scandal.  Hobbes  would  thus  seem  to  be 
in  favour  of  complete  religious  toleration  and  absolute 
indifference  of  the  State  in  religious  matters.  How  is 
this  reconcilable  with  the  theory  that  "religion  is 
law  ?  " 

The  explanation  is  not  far  to  seek.  The  endless 
religious  controversies  had  been  made  an  argument 
on  one  side  for  the  necessity  of  a  central  spiritual 
authority,  and  on  the  other  for  a  limitation  of  the 
essentials  of  religious  belief  to  the  points  upon  which 


234  HOBBES  [CHAP. 

all  men  were  agreed.  Hobbes  having,  in  words  at 
least,  to  accept  the  Christian  doctrines,  declares  that 
the  only  article  of  faith  "  which  the  Scripture  maketh 
simply  necessary  to  salvation  is  this,  that  Jesus  is  the 
Christ "  :  an  article  which,  as  we  have  seen,  he  manipu- 
lates strangely  enough.  Other  dogmas  need  not 
trouble  us.  "For  it  is  with  the  mysteries  of  our 
religion  as  with  wholesome  pills  for  the  sick ;  which 
swallowed  whole  have  the  virtue  to  cure ;  but  chewed 
are  for  the  most  part  cast  up  again  without  effect." 
Now  when  the  State  orders  us  to  swallow,  it  will 
allow  us  to  take  our  pills  whole.  The  State,  as  he 
says,  can  only  take  notice  of  our  words.  It  is  one  of 
the  vital  errors  of  the  false  teachers  to  "  extend  the 
power  of  the  law  to  the  very  thoughts  and  consciences 
of  men."  That,  he  intimates,  means  the  Inquisition, 
which  he  detests  as  heartily  as  any  man.  The  only 
interest  of  the  State  is  in  peace.  The  secular 
sovereign  will  not  want  to  rouse  theological  quarrels 
or  to  burn  his  subjects  to  enforce  dogmas.  Persecution 
is  the  natural  consequence  when  a  great  corporation 
has  been  built  up  upon  the  ground  of  a  dogmatic 
system,  and  when  all  its  interests  depend  upon  en- 
forcing orthodoxy.  The  destruction  of  such  a  power 
is  Hobbes's  real  aim.  If  we  subordinate  the  Church  to 
the  State,  the  secular  sovereign  will  be  no  longer  the 
tool  of  the  priest,  and,  even  if  he  prescribes  the  verbal 
acceptance  of  certain  dogmas,  he  will  take  care  that 
they  do  no  harm.  His  aim  will  be  to  suppress  contro-  > 
versy,  not  to  hinder  speculation. 

The  doctrine  of  toleration  was  developing,  though 
slowly  enough,  and  Hobbes  saw  one  difficulty  clearly. 
If  by  "  religion ';  we  mean  simply  the  creed  of  the 


iv.]  THE   STATE  235 

individual,  the  case  for  toleration  is  obvious  and  over- 
powering. It  must  be  wrong,  that  is,  to  punish  a  man 
for  accepting  what  he  believes  to  be  true.  But  a 
practical  difficulty  remains  when  "religion  "  is  regarded 
as  the  creed  of  an  organised  body,  which  has  therefore 
a  system  of  laws.  What  is  to  be  done  when  such  laws 
come  into  conflict  with  the  laws  of  the  State  ?  The 
difficulty  need  not  occur  if  as  a  matter  of  fact  the 
Church  and  State  do  not  represent  conflicting  theories, 
or  if  there  be  an  agreement  as  to  a  demarcation  of  their 
spheres  of  action.  But  as  religious  motives  affect 
men's  conduct  as  a  whole,  the  Church  can  hardly  be 
indifferent  to  every  part  of  the  action  of  the  State. 
When  differences  occur,  as  for  example  when  the  State 
undertakes  the  charge  of  education,  there  is  even  in  our 
own  day  a  great  difficulty  in  applying  the  principle  of 
toleration,  however  much  it  may  be  accepted  in  general 
terms.  In  Hobbes's  time,  such  difficulties  were  of 
course  much  greater.  The  Puritan  proposed  to  alter 
the  constitution  of  the  Church,  but  not  to  diminish  its 
authority  or  to  divorce  it  from  the  State.  As  sects 
multiplied,  the  principle  of  toleration  became  more 
widely  accepted ;  for  it  is  plain  that  when  you  are  in  a 
minority  of  one  your  only  logical  plea  for  liberty  must 
imply  universal  toleration.  Meanwhile  Hobbes,  dis- 
gusted by  the  struggles  of  rival  sects  and  the  claims  of 
the  Catholic  church  to  interfere  with  political  matters 
in  the  interest  of  the  hated  dogmatic  system,  took  a 
short  cut  to  a  solution.  Instead  of  trying  to  effect  a 
reconciliation,  he  would  simply  put  one  power  under 
the  feet  of  the  other,  and  the  dominant  power  should 
be  that  which  is  least  given  to  bigotry. 

In  some  respects  Hobbes's  solution  was  that  which 


236  HOBBES  [CHAP.  IT. 

actually  succeeded.  The  claim  of  the  pope  to  depose 
kings  was  of  little  practical  importance ;  and  Hobbes, 
like  his  countrymen,  seems  to  have  been  unduly 
nervous.  Giant  Pope,  though  far  from  being  so  de- 
crepit as  Bunyan  thought,  was  ceasing  to  have  much 
authority  over  the  political  world.  The  Church  of 
England  was  following  the  course  which  Hobbes 
desired.  He  complains  that  the  bishops  made  certain 
claims  to  independent  authority,  but  remarks  that  at 
any  rate  they  had  practically  submitted  to  the  king. 
That  tendency  developed,  and  Hobbes  would  have 
been  thoroughly  content  with  the  eighteenth  century, 
when  the  Church  ceased  to  make  any  claim  to  corporate 
power,  and  the  clergy  became  useful  dependants  on  the 
possessors  of  patronage. 


NOTE 

DURING  the  last  months  of  his  life  Sir  Leslie  Stephen 
was  writing  this  book.  When  he  could  no  longer  work 
he  asked  me  to  see  it  through  the  press.  Its  readers 
should,  I  think,  be  told  that  he  had  some  thoughts  of 
adding  to  it  a  few  sentences  about  the  influence  exer- 
cised by  Hobbes  on  later  philosophers,  the  French 
Encyclopaedists  and  the  English  Utilitarians,  and 
that  he  gave  me  some  notes,  by  the  aid  of  which  this 
addition  might  have  been  made.  However,  before  his 
death  I  had  sent  him  word  that  the  book  was  so  com- 
plete that  no  second  hand  ought  to  touch  it.  I  have 
only  made  those  small  changes  that  must  always  be 
made  whenever  a  book  is  printed.  He  expressly 
charged  me  to  acknowledge  his  debt  of  gratitude  to 
three  of  his  precursors :  his  friend  Groom  Eobertson, 
Dr.  F.  Tonnies,  and  M.  Georges  Lyon. 

F.  W.   MAITLAND. 


237 


INDEX 


Advancement  of  Learning  (Ba- 
con), 85. 

Althusius,  Johannes,  Politics  of, 
177. 

Andrewes,  Bishop,  179. 

Areopagitica  (Milton),  69. 

Aristotle,  118,  191. 

Arlington,  Lord,  60. 

Armada,  The  Spanish,  178. 

Athense  Oxonienses  (Anthony 
Wood),  2. 

Aubrey,  John,  2,  3,  6,  7,  8,  9, 11, 
12,  17,  25,  34,  37,  46,  48,  49,  57, 
60,  61,  65,  66. 

Augustine,  St.,  160. 

Austin,  John,  207,  208. 

Autobiography,  Hobbes's,  2. 

Ayton,  Sir  Robert,  11,  12. 

B 

Bacon,  1,  12, 13,  58,  61, 67,  76,  85. 
Behemoth,  4,  26,  29,  30,  60. 
Bellarmine,  Cardinal,  179,  229. 
Bentham,  Jeremy,  124,  207. 
Berkeley,  Bishop,  79,  99. 
Blount,  Charles,  68-9. 
Bodies,  Properties  of,  99. 
Boyle,  Robert,  51,  54,  76. 
Bramhall,  Bishop,  36, 50, 150, 151, 
154,  158,  160,  161,  162,  164,  165, 


Buchanan,  George,  58. 
Buckle,  Henry  T.,  86. 
Budget  of  Paradoxes  (de  Mor- 
gan), 55. 

Bunyan,  John,  236. 
Burnet,  Bishop,  60. 


Calvin,  160. 

Calvinism,  160. 

Cambridge,  University  of,  51, 60. 

Catholicism,  Roman,  30,  178, 179. 

Cause  and  Effect,  101  seq. 

Cavendish,  William,  1st  Earl  of 

Devonshire,  6,  7. 
Cavendish  Family,  6,  7,  8,  11,  13, 

15,  16,  19,  20,  36,  37,  38,  43,  46. 
Charles  I.,  27,  28,  186,197. 
II.,  39,  41,  45,  57,  58,  59,  60, 

67,  231. 

Chatsworth,  7,  14. 
Chillingworth,  William,  25. 
Christianity,  78. 

Church  and  State,  176setf.,222seg. 
Circle,  Squaring  the,  52-6. 
Clarendon,  Lord,  24-5,  26,  37,  41, 

42,  56,  60. 

Clinton,  Sir  George,  16. 
Cluverius's  Historia  Universalis, 

61. 

Coke,  Sir  Edward,  61,  206. 
Collins,  Anthony,  69. 


166,  167,  168,  169,  170. 
Brief  Lives  (Aubrey),  2. 
Browne,  Sir  Thomas,  72. 


Cominges,  Comte  de,  58. 
Comte,  155. 
Condillac,  94. 
239 


240 


HOBBES 


Constitution,  The  British,  193. 
Cooper,       Samuel       (miniature 

painter),  58. 
Copernicus,  77,  79. 
Cosin,  Bishop,  40,  45. 
Cowley,  46,  47,  48. 
Cromwell,  Oliver,  3,  41,  42,  198. 


D 

Davenant,  Sir  William,  46,  47. 
Decameron  Physiologicum,  55. 
De  Give,  34,  35,  37,  39,  42,  78, 150, 

173,  182,  190,  194,  201,  207,  220, 

222. 

De  Corpore,  50,  52,  66,  70,  77,  79, 
87,  88,  95,  98,  105,  114,  149,  150. 

De  Corpore  Politico,  114, 173, 182. 

Definitions,  92  seq. 

De  Homine,  114. 

De  Quincey,  15. 

Descartes,  20,  21,  32, 33,  37, 38, 65, 
78,  81,  82,  91,  98,  107,  111,  146. 

Determinism,  157  seq. 

Devonshire,  Earls  of,  see  Caven- 
dish. 

Dialogue  upon  the  Common  Law 

61,  193,  206. 

Dioptrique  (Descartes),  33. 
Divinity,  The  Schoolmen's,  78. 
Donne,  John,  179. 
Dort,  Synod  of,  158,  159,  160. 
Dreams,  115  seq. 
Dryden,  67. 
Du  Verdus,  36. 


Fell,  Dr.,  2. 
Filmer,  Sir  Robert,  49. 
Final  causes,  102  seq. 
Freewill,  157-72. 

G 

Galileo,  20,  21,  22,77,  79,  111,  125. 

Gassendi,  20,  24,  35,  37,  40,  45,  78. 

Geometry,  79-81. 

Gierke,  Professor,  177. 

Gladstone,  203. 

God,  Existence  of,  146 ;  attributes 

of,  147  seq. 

Godolphin,  Sidney,  25,  37,  38. 
Gondibert  (Davenant),  46,  48. 
Grotius,  49,  177. 


H 


E 

Eachard,  68. 
Edwards,  Jonathan,  159. 
Effect,  Cause  and,  101  seq. 
Elizabeth,  Queen,  233. 
Ethics  (Spinoza),  122. 

F 

Falkland,  Lord,  25,  26. 

Furquhar's  Constant  Couple,  68. 


Hales,  John,  25. 
Hamilton,  Sir  William,  85,  148. 
Hammond,  Henry,  25. 
Hampden,  John,  199. 

Harnack's Tf7ia«  is  Christianity? 

230. 

Hartley,  David,  118. 
Harvey,  William,  48,  78,  79,  81, 

111. 

Henry  VIII.,  6,  178. 
Heylin,  Peter,  20. 
History  of  the  Sabbath  (Heylin), 

20. 

Hobbes,   Thomas,  his  autobiog- 
raphy, 2;   family  history  and 
birth,  3;    school,   4;    goes  to 
Magdalen     Hall,     Oxford,    4; 
youthful  pursuits,  6;  tutor  to 
the  Cavendish  family,  6-8 ;  long 
connection  with  the  family,  8; 
makes  the  grand  tour,  8;  trans- 
lates Thucydides,  9, 12;  friend- 
ship with  eminent  men,  11,  12, 
13;    death  of  his  patron,  15; 
travels  with  another  pupil,  16  ; 
first  acquaintance  with  Euclid, 
17,  70,  71,  77,  80;  inquiries  into' 


INDEX 


241 


the  nature  of  motion,  18,  21,  77, 
78,  80;  devotes  himself  seri- 
ously to  philosophy,  19 ;  renews 
his  connection  with  the  Caven- 
dish family,  19,  20;  further 
travels,  20;  recognised  by  con- 
temporary philosophers,  20 ; 
new  acquaintances  at  home 
and  abroad,  20,  21,  25;  circu- 
lates summary  of  his  philo- 
sophical ideas,  27;  goes  to 
France  for  greater  safety,  27 ; 
controversy  with  Descartes, 
33 ;  publishes  De  Give,  34 ;  be- 
gins to  write  The  Leviathan, 
34 ;  tutor  to  the  exiled  Prince 
of  Wales,  38 ;  severe  illness, 
40;  publication  of  The  Levia- 
than, 40;  returns  to  England, 
41,  45;  accused  of  inconsis- 
tency and  disloyalty,  41,  42, 
43,  54;  suspected  of  atheism, 
44, 45,  59, 60,  67-9, 144,  150,  154 ; 
makes  acquaintance  of  various 
distinguished  men,  46-49;  con- 
troversy with  Bishop  Bram- 
hall,  50 ;  publishes  De  Corpore, 
50 ;  attempts  to  square  the  cir- 
cle, 52,  53,  55 ;  attacks  the  uni- 
versities, 51-7 ;  controversy 
with  John  Wallis,  52-5;  be- 
comes a  favourite  at  Court, 
58 ;  receives  a  pension  of  £100 
a  year  from  Charles  II.,  59;  ex- 
amination and  suppression  of 
his  writings  ordered,  59,  60; 
his  fame  abroad,  61 ;  writes  a 
long  Latin  poem  in  his  eightieth 
year,  61 ;  publishes  Decameron 
Physiolocjicum  in  his  ninetieth 
year,  55 ;  produces  a  work  on 
Common  Law,  61 ;  translates 
the  Iliad  and  Odyssey,  62; 
death,  63;  starting-point  of  his 
philosophical  speculations,  73, 
74,  84;  aim  of  his  philosophy, 
R 


84;  subject  of  philosophy,  84; 
theory  of  the  universe,  72  seq., 
80  seq. ;  divergence  from  Des- 
cartes's  views,  81-2 ;  theory  of 
logic,  87  seq.;  physical  science, 
98  seq.;  psychology,  109  seq. ; 
theology,  144  seq.;  freewill, 
157  seq.;  political  system,  173 
seq. ;  his  doctrine  of  motion, 
18,  21,  77, 78,  80,  81,  84  passim ; 
materialism  of  his  philosophy, 
82,  98  ;  philosophical  methods, 
12,  13 ;  ethical  theories,  21 ; 
hostility  to  established  beliefs, 
75 ;  attitude  towards  the  spirit- 
ual authorities,  29-32,  34,  45, 
57,  75;  heterodox  views,  76; 
comparison  of  Hobbes  with 
Bacon,  12,  13;  resemblance 
between  Hobbes  and  Herbert 
Spencer,  73 ;  a  great  thinker,  1 ; 
a  born  logician,  70;  Euclid  his 
type  of  reasoning,  88 ;  failure  as 
a  mathematician,  53;  intellec- 
tual energy  and  boldness,  55, 
56,  61,  62;  personal  timidity, 
56,  156;  shortcomings,  65;  con- 
temporary estimate  of  him,  67 ; 
general  opposition  aroused  by 
his  views,  67  ;  his  one-sidedness, 
71 ;  idiosyncrasies,  intellectual 
and  moral,  70 ;  his  unemotional 
nature,  72;  dogmatic  and  ag- 
gressive methods,  77 ;  views 
of  love,  132;  cynical  views  of 
human  nature,  139;  style,  9, 
10,  117  ;  favourite  authors,  65 ; 
personal  attractiveness,  23-4; 
sincerity  of  his  friendship,  23, 
24;  personal  appearance  and 
habits,  63-4;  devotion  to  music 
and  tennis,  64. 

Hobbes,  Thomas  (father),  3,  4. 

Mrs.  (mother),  3,  4. 

John  (brother),  4. 

Francis  (uncle),  4. 


242 


HOBBES 


"Hobbism,"74,  146. 
Hoeffdiug,  Professor,  84. 
Human  Nature,  108,    114,   120, 

123,  127,  132,  139. 
Hume,  99,  118,  229. 
Huxley,  81. 
Huygens,  58,  59. 


Ideas,  Association  of,  118-19. 
Imagination,  107,  115. 
Infinite,  The,  109, 149. 


James  I.,  7,  8,  179. 
Johnson,  Samuel,  201. 
Joiison,  Ben,  11,  12. 
Jowett,  Benjamin,  10. 

K 

Kenneth,  61. 

Kepler,  78. 

Kings,  Divine  right  of,  179  seq. 


Language,  92. 
Laud,  Archbishop,  31. 
Laughter,  130,  131. 
Law,  Moral,  214  seq. 
Leibnitz,  52. 

Leighton,  Archbishop,  24. 
Leviathan,  The,  1,  2,  32,  34,  36, 
38,  40,  41,  42,  43,  59,  60,  61,  65, 
68,  69,  73,  82,  114,  120,  127,  132, 
136,  150,  154,  173,  182,  193,  195, 
199,  206,  207,  211,  212,  220,  223. 

the  Great,  182, 183,  192, 194, 

195, 196,  197,  200,  204,  212. 
Lewes,  G.  H.,  117. 
Lilburne,  John,  206. 
Locke,  John,  1,  67. 
Logic,  87-97. 
Longornontanus,  38. 
Louis  XIV.,  59, 198. 


M 

Machiavelli,  185. 
Magdalen  Hall,  Oxford,  4,  5. 
Maine,  Sir  Henry,  61,  207. 
Malmesbury,  3. 
Mansel,  Henry,  148. 
Manwaring,  Bishop,  28. 
Mare  Clausum  (Selden),  20. 
Mary,  Queen  of  Scots,  178. 
Meditations   (Descartes),  32,  81, 

82. 

Meditationes  Sacrae  (Bacon),  85. 
Memory,  107. 
Mersenne,  Marin,  21, 22, 23, 24, 32, 

33,  35,  38,  40,  45,  56,  67,  78. 
Method  (Descartes),  32. 
Mill,  John,  94. 
Milton,  21,  24,  49,  58,  157,   158, 

205. 

Miracles,  228. 
Molesworth's  edition  of  Hobbes's 

Works,  70. 

"  Monarchomachist  '         contro- 
versy, 178. 
Montaigne,  67. 
Montesquieu,  193. 
More,  Sir  Thomas,  58. 
Morley,  Bishop,  25. 
Motion,  Nature  of,  18,  21,  77,  78, 
80-1,  84. 


N 

Names,  89-90. 

Natural    History    of    Religion 

(Hume),  155. 
Nature,  Law  of,  173  seq.,  186, 187, 

188,  189,  191,  208,  215. 
State  of,  185  seq. 


Newton,  Sir  Isaac,  52,  111. 
Nicholas,  Sir  Edward,  43,  44. 

O 

One-sidedness,  71. 
Oxford,  4,  5,  51,  52. 


INDEX 


243 


Paine,  Thomas,  206. 

Papacy,  The,  30, 178, 179,  221  seq., 

229,  230,  235,  236. 
Pascal,  67. 
Passions,  125  seq. 
Pepys,  Samuel,  60. 
Petty,  Sir  William,  37,  51. 
Phenomena,  Natural,  109  seq. 
Place,  100. 
Politics,  Hobhes's  System  of,  173 

seq. 

Pollock,  Sir  Frederic,  122. 
Presbyterianism,  31. 
Psychology,  114  seq. 
Punishment,  Eternal,  170-1. 
Puritans,  The,  5,  30. 
Pym,  John,  203. 

R 

Ravaillac,  178. 

Richelieu,  17. 

Rights  of  Man  (Paine),  206. 

Robertson,  Groom,  12,  55. 

Rochefoucauld,  139. 

Rousseau,  13. 

Royal  Society,  The,  51,  52,  54,  76. 

S 

Savile,  Sir  Henry,  51. 

Scargill,  60. 

Science,  Physical,  73,  75,  76,  82, 

98,  113. 

Selden,  John,  20,  48,  49. 
Self-preservation,  189  seq. 
Sensation,  18. 
Sense,  106-7. 
Seven  Problems,  231. 
Sheldon,  Bishop,  25. 
Sorbiere,  13,  35,  58,  59. 
Sordello  (Browning),  136. 
Sovereignty,  181,  186,  192  seq. 
Space,  98-9. 
Spencer,  Herbert,  73,  122,  148. 


Spinoza,  100,  101,  122, 156,  228. 

Spirits,  83. 

Spiritual  Power,  220  seq. 

Sprat,  13. 

Stewart,  Dugald,  85,  94. 

Suarez,  179. 

Sully,  Professor,  131. 

Swift,  5. 

T 

Table  Talk  (Selden),  49. 

Tenison,  Archbishop,  15. 

Testament,  The  Old,  226. 
—  The  New,  227. 

Thought,  84,  87-8. 

Thucydides,    Hobbes's    Transla- 
tion of,  9, 10,  12. 

Time,  98-9. 

Toland,  John,  69. 

Toleration,  Religious,  233  seq. 

Tolstoi,  202. 

Tonnies,  Dr.,  18,  55. 

Tractatus     Theologico-Politicus 
(Spinoza),  156,  228. 

Truth,  87. 

Tyrannicide,  178. 

U 

Universities,  The,  19,  50,  51,  52. 


Venice,  Constitution  of,  17. 
Voltaire,  66. 

W 

Waller,  Edmund,  16, 37, 40,46, 48. 
Wallis,  John,  41,  42,  52,  53,  54,  88. 
Warburtou,  William,  69. 
Ward,  Bishop,  51,  53. 
Wentworth,  Sir  Thomas,  16. 
White,  Thomas,  59,  60. 
Wood,  Anthony,  2. 
Words,  89-90. 
Wren,  Sir  Christopher,  51. 


RETURN     CIRCULATION  DEPARTMENT 

TO— ^      202  Main  Library 


LOAN  PERIOD  1 

HOME  USE 


ALL  BOOKS  MAY  BE  RECALLED  AFTER  7  DAYS 

Renewals  and  Recharges  may  be  made  4  days  prior  to  the  due  date. 

Books  may  be  Renewed  by  calling     642-3405. 


DUE  AS  STAMPED  BELOW 

1  6  1995 

.     ^             .          4*L       *f\^f 

OC1  0  2  1999 

APR  o  7  2<im 

FORM  NO.  DD6 


UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA,  BERKELEY 
BERKELEY,  CA  94720 


f  * 


<**•-. 


YB  247 1 5 


U.C.  BERKELEY  LIBRARIES 


CDS13flS33fl 


:  •  •"  '      •  *   '  •  V 


» » 


--•,*.:  ^-^*''-:- 


t 


,   -I: