Skip to main content

Full text of "Philosophical essays in honor of James Edwin Creighton"

See other formats


PHILOSOPHICAL   ESSAYS 


THE  MACMILLAN  COMPANY 

NEW  YORK   •   BOSTON  •   CHICAGO   •   DALLAS 
ATLANTA    •   SAN  FRANCISCO 

MACMILLAN  &  CO.,  LIMITED 

LONDON   •  BOMBAY   •  CALCUTTA 
MELBOURNE 

THE  MACMILLAN  CO.  OF  CANADA,  LTD. 

TORONTO 


as 


PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 


IN   HONOR  OF 


JAMES  EDWIN  CREIGHTON 


BY 

FORMER  STUDENTS 

IN  THE  SAGE  SCHOOL  OF  PHILOSOPHY  OF  CORNELL  UNIVERSITY 


IN  COMMEMORATION  OF  TWENTY-FIVE  YEARS'  SERVICE  AS 
TEACHER  AND  SCHOLAR 


$fork 

THE  MACMILLAN  COMPANY 
1917 


EDITOR 

GEORGE  HOLLAND  SABINE 


COPYRIGHT,  igi; 

BY  GEORGE  HOLLAND  SABINE 

Published  June,  1917. 

All  rights  reserved. 


QJo 

JAMES    EDWIN    CREIGHTON 
TEACHER,   SCHOLAR,   FRIEND 

THESE  ESSAYS  ARE  DEDICATED 

BY  SOME  OF  HIS    FORMER 

STUDENTS  AS  A  MARK  OF 

THEIR    GRATITUDE 

AND   ESTEEM 


PREFACE 

I  HAVE  been  asked  to  give  a  brief  account  of  JAMES  EDWIN 
CREIGHTON  as  a  teacher. 

I  deem  it  a  privilege  and  it  affords  me  genuine  pleasure 
to  join  his  former  students  in  this  tribute  to  Professor 
Creighton's  work  and  worth. 

The  ideal  professor  to-day  as  always  must  be  character 
ized  by  genuine  unworldliness.  He  is  in  the  world, — and 
the  more  he  participates  in  the  life  of  the  world  the  fuller 
and  the  more  vital  will  his  personality  become.  Yet  he  is 
not  of  the  world.  The  objects  which  most  men  pursue,— 
material  possessions,  place,  and  power, — are  not  for  him 
the  chief  ends  of  existence.  Intellectual  development  is 
the  aim  and  business  of  his  life, — intellectual  development 
first  in  himself  and  then  in  others.  In  a  world  given  over 
largely  and  enthusiastically  to  other  pursuits  he  stands  for 
the  things  of  the  mind.  He  realizes  himself  as  a  loyal  mem 
ber  of  the  kingdom  of  ideas,  of  knowledge  and  science,  of 
truth  and  beauty.  In  Heine's  phrase  he  is  a  knight  of  the 
Holy  Spirit. 

Professor  Creighton  for  a  quarter  of  a  century  has  em 
bodied  this  spirit  at  Cornell  University.  He  has  not  been 
indifferent  to  the  practical  problems  of  university  adminis 
tration  and  business;  he  has  taken  his  full  share  of  that  sort 
of  work  in  faculties  and  on  committees;  he  has  recognized 
and  asserted  that  even  the  highest  functions  of  a  university 
may  be  conditioned  by  its  income  and  endowments:  but 
he  has  always  stressed  and  kept  in  the  foreground  ,the  ideal 
ism  in  which  a  real  university  lives  and  moves  and  has  its 
being.  He  has  always  seen  clearly  what  the  proper  work 
and  function  of  the  professor  are,  and  that  insight  has  fur 
nished  the  regulative  and  dominating  conception  of  all  his 
thought  about  colleges  and  universities.  Such  a  man  is  an 
invaluable  asset  to  any  university  faculty.  And  that  Pro- 


viii  PREFACE 

fessor  Creighton's  colleagues  at  Cornell  recognize  his  in 
spiring  leadership  is  manifest  from  their  election  of  him  as 
Dean  of  the  Graduate  School, — that  department  in  which 
the  spirit  of  the  university  touches  the  culmination  of  its 
development. 

It  is  very  important  to  have  sound  views  of  the  place  and 
function  of  the  university  in  that  complex  whole  which  we 
call  human  civilization.  It  is  still  more  important  to  con 
vert  this  intellectual  apprehension  into  life  and  practice. 
Now  Professor  Creighton  has  for  many  years  seemed  to  me 
one  of  the  most  dynamic  and  vital  embodiments  to  be  found 
anywhere  of  the  highest  spirit  of  the  modern  university. 
Others  may  have  sought  different  objects,  none  of  them 
unworthy,  as,  for  example,  large  classes,  popularity,  eco 
nomic  advantages,  public  recognition;  but  for  him  the 
supreme  aim  and  business  of  life  has  been  growth  in  knowl 
edge  and  thought  and  the  stimulation  of  thinking  in  his 
students.  Others  may  have  become  discouraged  from  failure 
to  achieve  their  objects,  but  with  him,  the  condition  of 
success  being  in  himself,  failure  was  impossible.  Others 
may  have  lost  faith  in  the  worth  and  the  supremacy  of  the 
intellectual  life;  he,  always  achieving  inner  growth,  has 
been  a  live  coal  on  the  altar  of  truth.  His  faith  and  the 
faith  of  others  like  him  among  the  teachers  of  Cornell  Uni 
versity  has  kept  the  institution,  if  not  like  Moses'  bush 
"aglow  with  God,"  at  least  with  lamps  filled  and  wicks 
burning  in  preparation  for  the  coming  of  a  new  and  fuller 
revelation  of  the  Holy  Spirit  of  Reason. 

In  the  class  room  Professor  Creighton's  work  has  been 
highly  stimulating.  He  has  had  no  desire  for  big  numbers, 
but  his  students  include  many  of  the  ablest  and  most 
thoughtful  in  the  University.  And  for  a  not  inconsiderable 
proportion  of  them  his  work  marks  an  epoch  in  their  intel 
lectual  history.  Sometimes  Professor  Creighton  lectures, 
oftener  he  practices  the  Socratic  art  of  questioning,  always  he 
sees  to  it  that  the  students  read,  write,  and  think  for  them 
selves.  It  is  a  serious  business, — opening  the  eyes  of  the 
mind,  awakening  reflection,  bringing  young  persons  to  a  new 


PREFACE  ix 

consciousness  of  themselves,  of  the  world  which  they  per 
ceive,  and  of  the  relation  of  both  to  the  Infinite  Reality  on 
which  somehow  both  seem  to  depend,  their  being's  source 
and  destiny.  It  is  a  high  privilege  and  a  deep  responsibility 
to  traverse  themes  like  these  with  aspiring  and  ingenuous 
youth.  Every  one  who  knows  him  recognizes  that  Professor 
Creighton,  in  the  language  of  Scripture,  has  been  ordained 
and  sanctified  for  this  high  calling.  And  his  students,  many 
of  whom  are  teachers  scattered  all  over  the  Continent, 
loyally  and  affectionately  recognize  the  debt  of  gratitude 
they  owe  him  for  stimulating  them  to  venture  on  that  self- 
creative  activity  in  which  the  highest  intellectual  develop 
ment  must  always  consist. 

It  was  said  of  Dr.  Arnold,  the  famous  headmaster  of 
Rugby,  who  was  also  professor  at  Oxford,  that  his  chief  aim 
as  a  teacher  was  to  produce  moral  thoughtfulness  in  his 
pupils.  I  think  we  may  truthfully  say  that  Professor  Creigh- 
ton's  aim  has  been  to  develop  in  his  students  intellectual 
seriousness  as  well.  Perhaps,  as  the  world  is  rational  as 
well  as  moral,  there  may  not  be  so  much  real  difference  in 
the  aims  of  these  two  teachers  as  the  verbal  discrimination 
implies.  Be  that  as  it  may,  I  am  sure  that  all  former  stu 
dents  of  Professor  Creighton  will  feel  that  I  am  correctly 
voicing  their  sentiments  in  applying  to  him  the  words  writ 
ten  of  Dr.  Arnold  by  his  son  in  the  beautiful  memorial  poem 
entitled  "Rugby  Chapel": 

And  there  are  some,  whom  a  thirst 
Ardent,  unquenchable,  fires, 
Not  with  the  crowd  to  be  spent, 
Not  without  aim  to  go  round 
In  an  eddy  of  purposeless  dust, 
Effort  unmeaning  and  vain. 
****** 

But  thou  would'st  not  alone 
Be  saved,  my  father!  alone 
Conquer  and  come  to  thy  goal, 
Leaving  the  rest  in  the  wild. 
We  were  weary,  and  we 
Fearful,  and  we  in  our  march 


x  PREFACE 

Fain  to  drop  down  and  to  die. 
Still  thou  turnedst,  and  still 
Beckonedst  the  trembler,  and  still 
Gavest  the  weary  thy  hand. 
****** 

Therefore  to  thee  it  was  given 
Many  to  save  with  thyself; 
And,  at  the  end  of  thy  day, 
O  faithful  shepherd!  to  come, 
Bringing  thy  sheep  in  thy  hand. 

That  this  "faithful  shepherd"  may  for  many  years  to 
come  continue  at  Cornell  University  those  stimulating  and 
uplifting  ministrations  whose  first  two  and  a  half  decades 
this  volume  commemorates,  is  a  consummation  devoutly 
to  be  wished.  That  certainly  is  the  hope  and  fervent  desire 
of  our  academic  community, — of  the  teachers  and  students, 
past  and  present,  who  know  and  appreciate  the  inspiring 
service  he  renders  and  the  ennobling  influence  he  exerts. 

JACOB  GOULD  SCHURMAN. 


CONTENTS 

PAGE 

THE  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  IN  SPINOZA'S  ETHICS i 

Ernest  Albee,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Cornell  University. 

HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA 26 

Katherine  Everett  Gilbert. 

RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY 42 

George  Holland  Sabine,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the  University 
of  Missouri. 

FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE:  KANT 61 

Radoslav  Andrea  Tsanoff,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the  Rice 
Institute. 

MILL  AND  COMTE 78 

Nann  Clark  Barr,  Instructor  in  Philosophy  in  the  Connecticut 
College  for  Women. 

THE  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  OF  ALFRED  FOUILLEE 95 

Alma  Thorne  Penney. 

HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA 112 

Edgar  Lenderson  Hinman,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the  Uni 
versity  of  Nebraska. 

COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION 133 

G.|Watts  Cunningham,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Middlebury 
College. 

TIME  AND  THE  LOGIC  OF  MONISTIC  IDEALISM 151 

Joseph  Alexander  Leighton,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the  Ohio 
State  University. 

THE  DATUM 162 

Walter  Bowers  Pillsbury,  Professor  of  Psychology  in  the  Univer 
sity  of  Michigan. 

THE  LIMITS  OF  THE  PHYSICAL 175 

Grace  Andrus  de  Laguna,  Associate  Professor  of  Philosophy  in 
Bryn  Mawr  College. 

Is  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL? 184 

Henry  Wilkes  Wright,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Lake  Forest 
College. 


xii  CONTENTS 

PAGE 

THE  REVOLT  AGAINST  DUALISM 202 

Alfred  H.  Jones,  Assistant  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Brown 
University. 

SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM 214 

Edmund  H.  Hollands,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the  University 
of  Kansas. 

PRAGMATISM  AND  THE  CORRESPONDENCE  THEORY  OF  TRUTH 229 

Ellen  Bliss  Talbot,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Mount  Holyoke 
College. 

IDEA  AND  ACTION 245 

E.  Jordan,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Butler  College. 

SOME  PRACTICAL  SUBSTITUTES  FOR  THINKING 266 

Harvey  Gates  Townsend,  Associate  Professor  of  Education  in 
Smith  College. 

SELFHOOD 277 

Emil  Carl  Wilm,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Boston  University. 

MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT 290 

Robert  Morris  Ogden,  Professor  of  Education  in  Cornell  Univer 
sity. 

THE  ROLE  OF  INTENT  IN  MENTAL  FUNCTIONING 307 

John  Wallace  Baird,  Professor  of  Psychology  in  Clark  University. 

THE  RELATION  OF  PUNISHMENT  TO  DISAPPROBATION 318 

Theodore  de  Laguna,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Bryn  Mawr 
College. 

FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION:  A  CRITIQUE 328 

Edward  L.  Schaub,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Northwestern 
University. 


PHILOSOPHICAL    ESSAYS 


PHILOSOPHICAL    ESSAYS 

THE  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  IN  SPINOZA'S 

ETHICS 

ERNEST  ALBEE 

THE  consistency  of  Spinoza's  philosophical  system  has 
been  very  differently  rated,  on  the  whole,  by  the  earlier  and 
by  at  least  some  of  the  later  critics.  Of  course  it  was  long 
before  his  philosophy  received  anything  like  fair  criticism 
at  all,  on  account  of  odium  theologicum;  but  then  most  ac 
credited  critics  tended  to  over-emphasize  the  supposed  in 
exorable  logic  of  Spinoza's  procedure,  while  looking  askance 
at  his  premises  and  deprecating  his  conclusions.  An  in 
stance  of  this  was  Jacobi's  extravagant  statement  that  one 
could  not  be  said  to  understand  Spinoza  at  all,  if  a  single  line 
of  the  Ethics  remained  unclear.  On  the  other  hand,  Professor 
Erhardt,  in  his  comparatively  recent  and  very  able  critical! 
work  on  Spinoza,1  is  willing  that  we  should  regard  the 
philosopher  as  a  thinker  of  the  first  class  only  on  condition 
that  we  clearly  recognize  that  the  system  itself  is  distinctly  , 
second  class. 

It  is  a  little  hard  to  see  how  the  general  belief  in  Spinoza's 
thoroughgoing  consistency  arose, — probably  the  earlier 
critics  were  imposed  upon  by  the  external  and  essentially 
misleading  form  of  mathematical  demonstration,  as  there  is 
some  reason  to  suppose  that  Spinoza  himself  was, — but  if  we 
should  find  ourselves  obliged  even  to  reverse  the  former 
estimate  and  regard  his  system  as  one  of  the  most  incon 
sistent,  instead  of  the  most  consistent,  of  the  important 
systems  in  modern  philosophy,  this  would  not  necessarily 
reduce  Spinoza  himself  to  the  rank  of  a  second-rate  thinker. 

1  Die  Philosophie  des  Spinoza  im  Lichte  der  Kritik,  Leipzig,  1908. 


2  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

The  great  fault  of  a  mediocre  thinker  usually  is  that,  having 
been  born  with  a  capacity  for  only  the  narrowest  vision,  he 
hits  upon  some  one  category  or  set  of  categories,  and  then 
either  employs  his  one  method  recklessly  for  all  purposes  or 
obstinately  refuses  to  take  into  consideration  the  many  sides 
of  experience  to  which  his  method  obviously  does  not  apply. 
In  the  latter  case,  he  may  attain  to  a  considerable  degree  of 
consistency,  but  at  the  expense  of  truth  in  the  larger  and 
more  vital  sense.  Spinoza's  fault  was  plainly  the  opposite: 
standing  almost  at  the  threshold  of  technical  modern  philos 
ophy,  he  had  a  dazzling  vision  of  the  world  as  a  knowable 
totality;  but,  when  he  came  to  work  out  his  system  in  detail, 
when  he  came  to  deal  with  the  most  various  aspects  and 
implications  of  experience  on  the  assumption  that  they  must 
all  contribute  to  our  comprehension  of  reality  as  a  unified 
whole,  he  more  or  less  unconsciously  employed  and  in  an 
important  sense  helped  to  develop  various  categories,  which, 
however  valid  within  their  own  sphere  of  relevance,  could  by 
no  means  be  employed  in  the  sweeping  way  that  Spinoza 
did  actually  employ  them  without  serious  danger  of  conflict 
v  or  even  of  essential  contradiction. 

The  first  category  that  we  meet  with  in  Spinoza's  Ethics 
will  have  to  be  treated  with  rather  scant  courtesy,  even 
though  it  be  the  traditional  conception  of  ^substance':  (i) 
because  it  seems,  if  not  obsolete,  at  any  rate  decidedly  ob 
solescent;  but  more  particularly  (2)  because  we  are  here 
concerned  primarily,  not  with  the  validity  of  the  category 
itself,  but  rather  with  its  logical  significance  for  Spinoza's 
characteristic  treatment  of  the  problems  of  ethics.  It  must 
be  frankly  acknowledged  that  the  well-worn  formula,  "The 
order  and  connection  of  ideas  is  the  same  as  the  order  and 
connection  of  things,"  was  a  good  deal  more  than  a  mere 
catchword  for  early  rationalism  of  the  Cartesian  type,  though 
it  would  be  a  wild  and  illiterate  interpretation  to  assume  that 
this  was  merely  a  typical  case  of  the  fallacy  of  'representa 
tive  perceptionism.'  We  are  not  so  much  concerned  with  the 
fact  that  reality  itself  is  here  regarded  as  a  quasi-logical 
order,  with  which  the  order  and  connection  of  our  ideas,  so 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  3 

far  as  logical,  may  well  correspond,  as  with  the  fact  that  we 
are  here  confronted  with  the  fundamental  assumption  of  a 
logical  and  an  ontological  prius:  for  all  truth  there  must 
be  an  ultimate  logical  ground;  for  all  reality,  a  correspond 
ing  ontological  prius.  This  was  the  characteristic  procedure 
of  rationalism  of  the  Cartesian  type,  when  it  had  been  re 
duced  to  logically  consistent  form,  as  by  Spinoza.  Leibniz, 
indeed,  profoundly  modified  this  method  by  his  conception 
of  the  world  as  a  system  of  unique  but  interrelated  sub 
stances;  but  even  he  held  firmly  to  the  belief  in  certain 
logical  *  first  truths,'  which  were  supposed  to  be  such  in 
their  own  right,  so  that  they  would  hold  equally  well  in  a 
world  fundamentally  different  in  its  actual  constitution 
from  this  present  existing  one. 

But  we  are  here  concerned  only  with  Spinoza's  concep 
tion  of  an  ultimate  Substance,  which  he  calls  indifferently 
Deus  sive  Natura.  And,  for  the  present  purpose,  we  may 
safely  omit  all  consideration  of  the  well-known  technical 
difficulties  involved  in  the  important  distinction  between 
Natura  naturans  (God  and  his  *  attributes')  and  Natura 
naturata  (God  and  his  ' modes').  The  really  important 
consideration  is,  that  substance  is  regarded  as  that  which 
can  exist  in  itself,  while  everything  besides  substance  must 
exist  in  or  by  reason  of  something  else.  Here  we  find,  in  its 
baldest  form,  the  conception  of  the  logical  and  ontological 
prius,  always  tending  to  emerge  in  this  type  of  early  ra 
tionalism.  Moreover,  it  is  explicitly  stated, — what  in  any 
case  would  be  logically  implied, — that,  in  the  case  of  sub 
stance  as  here  conceived,  any  determination  would  be  a 
negation.1  So  much  for  substance,  whether  the  attributes 
be  taken  as  subjective  or  objective  in  their  ultimate  signif 
icance,  and,  at  this  distance,  it  is  not  difficult  to  see  that 
the  Erdmann-Fischer  controversy  on  this  question  was 
largely  irrelevant;  for,  if  "the  order  and  connection  of  ideas 
is  the  same  as  the  order  and  connection  of  things  [reality]," 
the  attributes  must  be  both  subjective  and  objective.  For 

1  The  contrary  logic  of  Leibniz'  conception  of  substance  is  worth  notic 
ing  in  this  connection. 


4  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

want  of  a  better  name,  I  shall  call  this  assumption  the  pos 
tulate  of  ' logical  parallelism.'  -  It  is  highly  convenient  to 
have  a  label,  for  we  shall  soon  encounter  another  postulate, 
equally  important  for  Spinoza,  which  cannot  be  reconciled 
with  this. 

Now  the  question  naturally  arises,  whether  substance, 
in  this  sense,  is  a  legitimate  principle  of  explanation  at  all, 
or  merely  the  hypostatization  of  the  conception  of  ultimate 
logical  ground.  At  any  rate,  we  are  confronted  with  the 
apparently  contradictory  ideals  of  an  absolutely  indeter 
minate  substance,  on  the  one  hand,  and,  on  the  other  hand, 
a  world  in  some  sense  determined  in  infinitum.  The  mys 
terious  transition  from  the  one  point  of  view  to  the  other 
is  apparent.  The  world  regarded  as  absolutely  determined, 
in  some  as  yet  undefined  sense,  finds  its  ultimate  ground  in 
substance;  while  the  only  thing  that  we  are  supposed  really 
to  know  about  substance  is  that,  in  its  true  nature,  if  such 
an  expression  be  permissible,  it  is  absolutely  indeterminate. 
The  infinites  of  mathematics  are  now  held  to  be  amenable 
to  strictly  scientific  treatment;  but  the  Absolute  is  more 
refractory,  particularly  when  taken  abstractly  as  that  which 
exists  'in  itself.' 

The  first  fifteen  propositions  of  Part  I  of  the  Ethics  prac 
tically  amount  only  to  a  more  comprehensive  definition  of 
substance  as  ultimate  ground.  In_J^roposition  xvi  we  are 
told:  "From  the  necessity  of  the  divine  nature  must  follow 
an  infinite  number  of  things  in  infinite  ways — that  is,  all 
things  which  can  fall  within  the  sphere  of  infinite  intellect."  1 
This  reminds  one  too  much  of  the  crude  and  literal  inter 
pretation  of  the  logic  of  chance,  according  to  which  all 
computations  would  actually  be  realized  in  an  infinite  series. 
But  it  is  more  pertinent  to  remark  that  this  is  the  very 

1  Vol.  II,  p.  59  of  the  Elwes  translation  of  Spinoza's  '  Chief  Works,' 
which  will  be  followed  in  quotations.  Page  references  will  also  be  to  this 
translation.  The  White-Stirling  translation  might  have  been  preferred  for 
quotations,  except  for  certain  peculiarities  of  philosophical  terminology, 
which  make  it  inconvenient  for  the  purpose.  The  Van  Vloten  and  Land 
text  of  the  original  is,  of  course,  taken  as  standard. 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES 

opposite  of  any  intelligible  application  of/the  conception 
of  logical  ground:  nothing  (in) particular  is  here  regarded 
as  the  ultimate  ground  of  everything  in  particular.  Of 
course  we  are  not  disposing  of  the  Absolute  thus'  easily; 
the  conception  of  the  Absolute  and  the  Finite  as  essential 
correlatives  gives  rise  to  problems  that  we  cannot  even 
glance  at  here.  On  the  other  hand,  the  Absolute  as  the 
In-Itself,  upon  which  all  that  is  finite  depends,  while  it 
exists  in  happy  unconcern  of  the  Finite  in  all  its  practically 
infinite  specific  manifestations,  is  already  discredited.  That 
this  is  not  an  imaginary  difficulty  will  be  seen  from  Proposi 
tion  xxix,  the  'caption'  of  which  reads:  "Nothing  in  the 
universe  is  contingent,  but  all  things  are  conditioned  to 
exist  and  operate  in  a  particular  manner  by  the  necessity 
of  the  divine  nature."  l  In  other  words,  the  world  con 
sidered  as  Natura  naturata,  with  its  endless  relativity  and 
complete  determinateness,  is  referred  to  Natura  naturans, 
where  any  determination  would  be  a  negation, — apart  from 
the  differentiation  of  the  ' attributes'  themselves,  presum 
ably  an  illogical  exception. 

The  famous  Appendix  to  Part  I  of  the  Ethics,  in  which 
Spinoza  seems  to  dispose  summarily,  not  only  of  all  anthro 
pomorphic  conceptions  of  (Divine)  Final  Cause,  but  of  all  • 
moral  values  as  well,  is  less  important  than  would  appear, 
for  the  absolute  determinism  apparently  contended  for  is 
not  as  yet  referred  to  any  intelligible  logical  ground  or 
practical  category.2 

It  is  different  when  we  pass  to  Part  II,  "Of  the  Nature  and 
Origin  of  the  Mind."  Here  we  find  the  original  form  of  the 
theory  of  parallelism,  although  the  motive  of  the  philosopher 
in  developing  this  conception  was  presumably  metaphysical 
rather  than  scientific.  The  assumption  of  an  infinite  number 
of  attributes, — as  if  anything  less  than  an  infinite  number 
would  be  unworthy  of  the  'infinite  essentiality'  of  God,— 
we  may,  of  course,  pass  over  as  irrelevant:  the  only  attributes 
that  we  know  of  are  Thought  and  Extension,  and  to  these 

1  P.  68. 

2  This  whole  problem  will  be  considered  later  in  another  context. 


6  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

alone,  naturally,  Spinoza  devotes  his  attention.  The  two 
'substances'  of  Descartes  are  simply  degraded  to  *  attri 
butes'  or  aspects  of  the  one  only  Substance,  Deus  sive  Natura; 
and  the  assumption  is,  that  any  mode  of  substance  is  neces 
sarily  manifested  on  the  plane  of  both  attributes  and  with 
equal  adequacy.  Like  most  ontological  explanations,  this  one 
is  lacking  in  real  cogency;  for  Spinoza  pays  the  price  of  prac 
tical  dualism  for  the  theoretical  satisfaction  of  maintaining 
an  ontological  monism.  At  any  rate,  however,  he  has  a  real 
working  hypothesis  at  last,  even  if  we  must  regard  the  met 
aphysical  justification  of  this  hypothesis  as  questionable. 
But  it  will  soon  appear  that  he  has  adopted  a  hard  task 
master.  He  has  evaded,  rather  than  solved,  the  difficult 
philosophical  problem  regarding  the  relations  between  mind 
and  body;  and,  in  adopting  this  standpoint  of  parallelism, 
convenient  and  legitimate  for  many  practical  purposes  of 
science,  so  long  as  it  is  not  taken  in  a  metaphysical  sense, 
he  has  cut  off  all  possibility  of  consistently  maintaining,  in 
the  logical  sense,  the  original  and  fundamental  postulate, 
that  "the  order  and  connection  of  ideas  is  the  same  as  the 
order  and  connection  of  things/' — a  postulate  crude  enough 
in  its  original  formulation,  but  in  some  sense  true,  if  thought 
is  able  to  cope  with  reality  at  all, — and,  what  is  even  more 
important  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  present  inquiry, 
he  has  adopted  a  principle  which  can  never  so  much  as  per 
mit  a  serious  consideration  of  moral  values,  however  uncon 
ventionally  regarded.  Physical  and  mental  processes  do 
factually  correspond,  and  that  is  the  end  of  the  matter. 
For  convenience,  I  shall  call  this  assumption  the  postulate 
of  'psycho-physical  parallelism,'  in  spite  of  the  unfortu 
nately  modern  sound  of  the  term;  for  it  suggests  both  the 
possible  legitimate  application  and  the  inevitable  limitation 
of  the  sphere  of  application  of  this  category. 

It  must  be  remembered  that  what  is  attempted  here  is  a 
logical  analysis  and  criticism  of  Spinoza's  procedure,  not  a 
running  summary  of  his  actual  treatment  of  the  problems 
examined.  The  bulk  of  Part  II  is  devoted  to  the  con 
sideration  of  metaphysical  and  logical  problems,  although 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  7 

the  postulate  of  '  psycho-physical  parallelism,'  as  I  have 
ventured  to  call  it,  assumed  throughout  this  Part,  is  really 
relevant  only  to  the  psychological  method.  The  result 
ing  confusion  of  metaphysical,  logical,  and  psychological 
problems  hardly  need  detain  us;  for  the  really  essential 
matter,  from  the  point  of  view  of  ethics,  is,  that  Spinoza 
here  first  develops,  in  intelligible  form,  the  conception  of 
a  thoroughgoing  quasi-physical  determinism,  which  would 
really  be  as  fatal  to  a  satisfactory  treatment  of  theory  of 
knowledge  as  to  a  satisfactory  treatment  of  ethics  itself. 

Proposition  xxxvi  reveals  the  essential  difficulty.  The 
'  caption'  reads:  "Inadequate  and  confused  ideas  follow  by 
the  same  necessity  as  adequate  or  clear  and  distinct  ideas."  x 
"Inadequate  and  confused  ideas"  may  or  may  not  follow 
i necessarily';  but  it  is  fair  to  assume  that  they  do  not 
"follow  by  the  same  necessity  as  adequate  or  clear  and  dis 
tinct  ideas,"  if  there  be  such  a  thing  as  truth  at  all.  This  is 
simply  a  case  of  the  confusion  of  categories.  That  Spinoza 
himself  saw  no  difficulty  here  is  sufficiently  evident  from 
the  fact  that  he  first  explicitly  states  the  postulate  of 
*  logical  parallelism'  in  this  Part,  which  is  dominated,  on 
the  whole,  by  the  postulate  of  'psycho-physical  parallelism.' 
In  truth,  it  is  difficult  to  escape  the  belief  that  the  first 
formula  is  sometimes  understood  in  an  ambiguous  sense  by 
Spinoza,  so  that  it  answers  equally  well  to  express  the  logic 
ally  distinct  postulates  of  'logical'  and  'psycho-physical  par 
allelism.' 

It  is  generally  assumed  that  in  Part  III  of  the  Ethics,  "On 
the  Origin  and  Nature  of  the  Emotions,"  Spinoza's  problem 
is  almost  wholly  scientific,  though  it  is  plain  from  the  start 
that  he  proposes  to  use  his  results  in  the  interest  of  his  ethical 
theory.  It  must  be  admitted  that  he  himself  says,  at  the 
close  of  his  preliminary  observations :  "  I  shall  consider  human 
actions  and  desires  in  exactly  the  same  manner,  as  though  I 
were  concerned  with  lines,  planes,  and  solids."  2  And  yet, 
the  'caption'  of  Proposition  i  reads:  "Our  mind  is  in  cer 
tain  cases  active,  and  in  certain  cases  passive.  In  so  far 
1  P.  109.  2  p.  I29> 


8  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

as  it  has  adequate  ideas,  it  is  necessarily  active,  and  in  so 
far  as  it  has  inadequate  ideas,  it  is  necessarily  passive." 
This  distinction,  all-important  for  both  Spinoza's  theory  of 
knowledge  and  his  ethical  theory,  as  will  presently  appear, 
is  plainly  out  of  place  in  the  present  connection,  where  the 
explanations  are  doubtless  intended  to  be  causal  in  the  sense 
of  ordinary  science. 

The  preliminary  definitions  of  pleasure  and  pain  are  con 
fusing,  because,  taken  literally,  as  they  sometimes  are  by 
popular  commentators,  they  seem  to  imply  that  all  emo 
tions  are  '  passions/  a  position  perhaps  compatible  with 
the  characteristic  standpoint  of  psychology,  but  which,  if 
accepted  in  the  ultimate  sense,  would  make  Spinoza's  ethical 
theory  (and,  for  that  matter,  any  real  ethical  theory)  im 
possible.  These  definitions,  as  given  in  the  'note'  to  Prop 
osition  xi,  are  as  follows:  "By  pleasure  ...  in  the  fol 
lowing  propositions  I  shall  signify  a  passive  state  wherein  the 
mind  passes  to  a  greater  perfection.  By  pain  I  shall  signify 
a  passive  state  wherein  the  mind  passes  to  a  lesser  perfection"  1 
Desire  has  been  defined  already  as  "appetite  with  conscious 
ness  thereof";  and  Spinoza  adds:  "Beyond  these  three 
[pleasure,  pain,  desire]  I  recognize  no  other  primary  emo 
tion," — a  simplification  that  is  supposed  to  be  a  radical  im 
provement  upon  Descartes.  Spinoza's  matter  of  fact  ex 
planation  of  the  origin  of  the  passions, — which  has  often 
been  over-praised,  but  which  must  always  be  treated  respect 
fully  as  an  interesting  pioneer  attempt  in  a  difficult  field,— 
need  not  detain  us  in  so  far  as  it  is  merely  a  psychological 
explanation,  good  or  bad  in  the  scientific  sense;  but  the  cross 
currents  of  the  argument  need  watching.  The  first  part  of 
the  'note'  to  Proposition  xxxix  reads:  "By  good  I  here 
mean  every  kind  of  pleasure,  and  all  that  conduces  thereto, 
especially  that  which  satisfies  our  longings,  whatsoever  they 
may  be.  By  evil  I  mean  every  kind  of  pain,  especially  that 
which  frustrates  our  longings."  In  this  particular  case,  the 
context  seems  to  imply  that  this  is  only  a  provisional  defini 
tion;  and  so  it  must  emphatically  be  regarded,  for  in  his 

1  P.  138. 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  9 

treatment  of  ethics  proper  Spinoza  is  as  far  as  possible  from 
holding  to  '  quantitative  hedonism/  though  he  is  equally 
far  from  subscribing  to  any  form  of  mere  asceticism.  The 
confusion  is  made  worse  by  the  contrary  implication  of 
Proposition  LVI,  the  '  caption  '  of  which  reads:  "There  are  as 
many  kinds  of  pleasure,  of  pain,  of  desire,  and  of  every  emo 
tion  compounded  of  these,  ...  as  there  are  kinds  of  objects 
whereby  we  are  affected."  l 

But  the  transition  from  the  (predominantly)  psychological 
to  the  (predominantly)  ethical  point  of  view  takes  place 
suddenly  enough  in  the  next  proposition  but  one  (Prop. 
LVIII):  "Besides  pleasure  and  desire,  which  are  passivities 
or  passions,  there  are  other  emotions  derived  from  pleasure 
and  desire,  which  are  attributable  to  us  in  so  far  as  we  are 
active."  And  Proposition  LIX  reads:  "Among  all  the  emo 
tions  attributable  to  the  mind  as  active,  there  are  none  which 
cannot  be  referred  to  pleasure  or  desire." 

Here,  then,  at  the  end  of  Spinoza's  (mainly)  psychological 
treatment  of  the  emotions,  as  given  in  Part  III,  we  are  in  a 
position  to  look  forward  as  well  as  back.  The  main  drift  of 
the  argument  has  been  that  our  emotions  are  as  susceptible 
of  causal  explanation  as  are  any  of  the  other  phenomena  of 
nature.  From  this  point  of  view,  of  course,  it  makes  no  real 
difference  whether  the  mind  is  determined  by  'adequate' 
or  by  *  inadequate'  ideas;  the  all-important  consideration 
is  that  it  is  always  determined,  not  'free.'  But,  from  the 
point  of  view  of  logic  and  theory  of  knowledge,  as  well  as 
from  the  point  of  view  of  ethics,  it  makes  every  difference 
whether  we  are  'active'  (determined  by  adequate  ideas) 

1  P.  168. 

2  P.  171.     It  should  be  noted  that  cupiditatem  is  translated  'pain'  by 
Elwes,  not  'desire,'  as  in  the  above  corrected  translation.     Of  course 
this  is  only  'a  slip  of  the  pen'  in  the  literal  sense  of  the  words  (the  text 
used  is  not  at  fault  in  this  case);  but  it  should  be  noted  that,  whereas  the 
emotions  which   are   'passions'   are   variously  explainable   in   terms   of 
pleasure,  pain,  and  desire,  according  to  Spinoza,  pain  cannot  be  involved 
in  the  case  of  the  emotions  which  are  'activities'  as  opposed  to  'pas 
sions,'  for  pain  goes  with  'passivity'  alone.     The  meaning  of  'activity' 
and  'passivity,'  as  understood  by  Spinoza,  will  be  more  evident  later. 


io  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

or  *  passive'  (determined  by  inadequate  ideas).  Not  that 
we  are  ever  determined  by  ideas  as  such,  whether  ' adequate' 
or  'inadequate,' — for  Spinoza  realizes  that  the  mind  func 
tions  as  a  whole, — but  we  are  as  capable  of  being  determined 
by  emotions  inseparably  connected  with  our  intellectual 
nature  as  we  are  of  being  determined  by  emotions  that  are 
mere  '  passions.'  Hence  the  possibility  of  truth  and  free 
dom,  though  the  consideration  of  these  problems  carries  us 
far  beyond  the  ordinary  point  of  view  of  psychology. 

In  turning  to  Parts  IV  and  V,  we  are  prepared  to  find 
Spinoza's  direct  treatment  of  the  problems  of  ethics,  sup 
posed  to  be  based  upon  the  foundations  already  laid.  The 
titles  are  sufficiently  descriptive  of  the  main  trend  of  the 
argument:  it  will  be  remembered  that  Part  IV  is  "Of  Human 
Bondage,  or  the  Strength  of  the  Emotions;"  Part  V,  "Of 
the  Power  of  the  Understanding,  or  of  Human  Freedom." 
Even  from  the  beginning  of  Spinoza's  argument  (in  Part  IV), 
however,  confusion  is  apparent  to  the  careful  reader.  He 
first  practically  recapitulates  the  drift  of  the  argument  of 
the  Appendix  to  Part  I.  'Perfection'  and  'imperfection' 
are  purely  relative  and  human  designations;  the  standard 
is  always  a  preconceived  idea,  traceable  to  some  subjective 
desire  on  the  part  of  him  who  evaluates.  As  in  the  previous 
form  of  the  same  argument,  Spinoza  holds  that  "the  eternal 
and  infinite  Being,  which  we  call  God  or  Nature,  acts  by  the 
same  necessity  as  that  whereby  it  exists."  x  Accordingly, 
"a  cause  which  is  called  final  is  nothing  else  but  human 
desire,  in  so  far  as  it  is  considered  as  the  origin  or  cause  of 
anything."  The  reason  why  this  fundamental  truth  is  not 
generally  recognized  is  that  "men  are  generally  ignorant  of 
the  causes  of  their  desires."  This  brief  argument  requires  a 
little  dissection;  the  last  part  is  plainly  a  reaffirmation  of  the 
position  previously  taken  by  Hobbes,  that  all  so-called 
'final'  causes  are  reducible  to  terms  of  'efficient'  causes. 
But  what  was  consistent  for  Hobbes,  who  regarded  mechan 
ism  as  the  ultimate  category,  was  plainly  inconsistent  for 
Spinoza,  whose  whole  procedure  tends  to  reduce  what  we 

1  P.  188. 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  II 

ordinarily  mean  by  'efficient'  causality  to  terms  of  logical 
ground  and  consequent.  We  are  not  yet  concerned  with  the 
question  whether  freedom  can  be  provided  for  in  Spinoza's 
system:  we  are  merely  bound  to  recognize  that  the  possibil 
ity  of  freedom  cannot  be  brushed  aside  in  the  name  of 
mechanism,  unless  Spinoza  is  prepared  to  recognize  mech 
anism  as  the  ultimate  category.  The  'necessary  existence' 
of  God,  from  which  the  mechanical  'necessity'  of  natural 
events  is  supposed  to  derive,  is  of  course  to  be  understood 
as  a  logical  and  ontological  necessity,  and  therefore  as  on 
an  entirely  different  plane. 

Again,  as  in  the  Appendix  to  Part  I,  Spinoza  holds  that 
the  terms  'good'  and  'bad'  "are  merely  modes  of  think 
ing,  or  notions  which  we  form  from  the  comparison  of  one 
thing  with  another."  "For  instance,  music  is  good  for 
him  that  is  melancholy,  bad  for  him  that  mourns;  for  him 
that  is  deaf,  it  is  neither  good  nor  bad."  But  this  is  a  puz 
zling  introduction  to  what  follows,  for  we  are  immediately 
told  that  these  terms  should  be  retained.  The  philosopher 
says:  "In  what  follows,  then,  I  shall  mean  by  'good'  that 
which  we  certainly  know  to  be  a  means  of  approaching  more 
nearly  to  the  type  of  human  nature,  which  we  have  set  before 
ourselves;  by  'bad,'  that  which  we  certainly  know  to  be  a 
hindrance  to  us  in  approaching  the  said  type."  l  This  sounds 
as  dogmatic  on  the  side  of  constructive  ethical  theory  as  the 
preceding  passages  had  been  to  the  contrary  effect,  and  the 
same  tone  is  preserved  in  the  'Definitions.'  There  Spinoza 
says:  "By  good  I  mean  that  which  we  certainly  know  to  be 
useful  to  us."  And  again:  "By  evil  I  mean  that  which  we 
certainly  know  to  be  a  hindrance  to  us  in  the  attainment 
of  any  good."  His  manner  of  justifying  our  'certainty' 
as  to  what  is  good  or  bad  for  us  in  the  ethical  sense  will  be 
considered  in  due  time.  Here  we  need  only  notice  that 
Spinoza  has  already  turned  his  back  upon  all  points  of  view 
which  rule  out  ethical  evaluations  as  subjective  and  illusory. 
This  means  an  essential  reversal  of  what  had  before  seemed 
to  be  his  attitude  toward  the  problem  of  morality. 

1  P.  189. 


12  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

The  general  standpoint  of  Part  IV,  "Of  Human  Bondage, 
or  the  Strength  of  the  Emotions,"  presents  no  special  dif 
ficulty,  at  any  rate  so  long  as  we  confine  ourselves  to  the 
attempt  to  understand  Spinoza's  own  position.  From  his 
point  of  view,  it  is  useless  to  discuss  human  conduct  on  the 
basis  of  abstract  ideals  conventionally  accepted.  We  must 
begin  by  definitely  recognizing  our  human  limitations,  and 
that  means  regarding  man,  from  one  point  of  view  at  least, 
as  a  part  of  the  order  of  nature,  "infinitely  surpassed  by 
the  power  of  external  causes"  (Prop.  in).  And  he  adds: 
"It  is  impossible,  that  man  should  not  be  a  part  of  Nature, 
or  that  he  should  be  capable  of  undergoing  no  changes,  save 
such  as  can  be  understood  through  his  nature  only  as  their 
adequate  cause"  (Prop.  iv).  In  other  words,  the  power 
of  mere  passion  is  not  our  own  power,  but  rather  that  of 
external  causes,  for  here  we  are  by  definition  'passive'  or 
'in  bondage.'  And  we  must  not  look  for  release  to  'rea 
son,'  abstractly  considered.  Later  rationalistic  moralists 
might  well  have  given  more  heed  to  Spinoza's  frank  ac 
knowledgment:  "An  emotion  can  only  be  controlled  or 
destroyed  by  another  emotion  contrary  thereto,  and  with 
more  power  for  controlling  emotion"  (Prop.  vn).  This  is 
reenforced  by  the  later  statement:  "A  true  knowledge  of 
good  and  evil  cannot  check  any  emotion  by  virtue  of  being 
true,  but  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  considered  as  an  emotion" 
(Prop,  xi v).1 

It  will  soon  appear  that  Part  IV  is  not  by  any  means 
wholly  or  mainly  devoted  to  a  consideration  of  "Human 
Bondage."  In  the  'note'  to  the  proof  of  Proposition  xvui, 
Spinoza  says:  "In  these  few  remarks  I  have  explained  the 
causes  of  human  infirmity  and  inconstancy,  and  shown  why 
men  do  not  abide  by  the  precepts  of  reason.  It  now  re 
mains  for  me  to  show  what  course  is  marked  out  for  us  by 
reason,  which  of  the  emotions  are  in  harmony  with  the  rules 
of  human  reason,  and  which  of  them  are  contrary  thereto." 
And  he  anticipates  his  further  argument  by  showing  in  a 
general  way  that  "reason  makes  no  demands  contrary  to 

1  P.  198. 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  13 

nature."  After  insisting  upon  the  necessity  of  self-preserva 
tion  in  terms  that  suggest  Hobbes,  he  concludes  in  a  differ 
ent  spirit:  "Therefore,  to  man  there  is  nothing  more  useful 
than  man — nothing,  I  repeat,  more  excellent  for  preserving 
their  being  can  be  wished  for  by  men,  than  that  all  should 
so  in  all  points  agree,  that  the  minds  and  bodies  of  all  should 
form,  as  it  were,  one  single  mind  and  one  single  body,  and 
that  all  should,  with  one  consent,  as  far  as  they  are  able, 
endeavor  to  preserve  their  being,  and  all  with  one  consent 
seek  what  is  useful  to  them  all."  1 

In  the  argument  that  follows,  Spinoza  endeavors  to  ex 
plain  the  function  of  reason  in  the  moral  life.  If  the  de 
tailed  treatment  of  this  problem  leaves  a  good  deal  to  be 
desired,  as  judged  by  the  more  exacting  technical  standards 
of  to-day,  it  should  always  be  remembered  that  our  philoso 
pher  was  the  first  great  rationalistic  moralist  in  the  sense 
of  modern  philosophy,  and  that,  when  he  finally  comes  to 
deal  with  the  special  problems  of  ethics,  he  shows  far  greater 
consistency  and  real  philosophical  grasp  than  in  the  first 
three  Parts  of  the  Ethics.  In  other  words,  Spinoza  was  not 
merely  a  great  pioneer  in  ethical  theory,  but  a  pioneer  who 
instinctively  avoided  many  of  the  mistakes  that  we  have 
come  to  regard  as  characteristic  of  the  procedure  of  later 
rationalists.  In  spite  of  certain  infelicities  of  expression, 
he  always  tends  to  regard  reason  as  internally  regulative 
rather  than  as  externally  legislative.  For  example,  he  says: 
"In  so  far  as  men  are  assailed  by  emotions  which  are  pas 
sions,  they  can  be  contrary  one  to  another"  (Prop,  xxxiv); 
whereas,  "In  so  far  only  as  men  live  in  obedience  to  reason, 
do  they  always  necessarily  agree  in  nature"  (Prop.  xxxv). 
This  may  sound  commonplace  enough;  but  the  meaning, 
plain  from  the  context,  is,  that  the  true  difference  between 
the  life  of  unregulated  passion  and  the  life  of  reason  is  not 
the  difference  between  being  determined  by  feeling  alone 
and  being  determined  by  reason  alone, — both  obvious 
impossibilities, — but  rather  the  difference  between  being 
determined  by  'external  causes'  ('bondage'),  where  the 

1  P.  202. 


I4  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

internal  rational  control  is  perhaps  at  a  minimum,  and 
being  determined  by  emotions  that  themselves  bear  witness 
to  the  internally  organizing  agency  of  reason  (' freedom'). 
"The  highest  good  of  those  who  follow  virtue  is  common 
to  all,  and  therefore  all  can  equally  rejoice  therein"  (Prop. 
xxxvi).  The  harmony  suggested  is  not  an  externally 
arranged  harmony,  'preestablished'  in  the  bad  sense,  but 
a  harmony  developing  from  within  in  proportion  as  the 
emotional  life  is  organized  in  terms  of  reason. 

And  Spinoza's  ethical  ideal,  exacting  as  it  will  prove  to  be 
in  some  respects,  is  singularly  free  from  that  rigorism  for  its 
own  sake  that  has  done  so  much  to  discredit  some  of  the 
later  forms  of  rationalistic  theory.  Though  not  the  end 
directly  to  be  sought,  "pleasure  in  itself  is  not  bad  but 
good:  contrariwise,  pain  in  itself  is  bad"  (Prop.  XLI).  In 
deed,  one  is  not  likely  to  forget  the  rather  quaint  remark 
made  in  a  later  'note'  (appended  to  Prop.  XLV)  :  "I 
say  it  is  the  part  of  a  wise  man  to  refresh  and  recreate 
himself  with  moderate  and  pleasant  food  and  drink,  and 
also  with  perfumes,  with  the  soft  beauty  of  growing  plants, 
with  dress,  with  music,  with  many  sports,  with  theatres, 
and  the  like,  such  as  every  man  may  make  use  of  without 
injury  to  his  neighbor."  1  There  is  no  word  of  disparage 
ment  here  or  elsewhere  in  the  Ethics  for  the  commonly 
recognized  'good  things  of  life,'  which  the  philosopher 
himself  sacrificed  so  cheerfully  for  freedom  and  the  higher 
'blessed  life.'  2 

The  often  quoted  theses  that  "Pity,  in  a  man  who  lives 
under  the  guidance  of  reason,  is  in  itself  bad  and  useless" 
(Prop.  L);  that  "Humility  is  not  a  virtue,  or  does  not  arise 

1  P.  219. 

2  The  difference  between  the  tone  that  Spinoza  adopts  here  and  that 
which  he  had  employed  in  the  Improvement  of  the  Understanding  and, 
still  more,  in  the  earlier  Short  Treatise,  is  too  obvious  to  require  more 
than  passing  mention.    Of  course  this  does  not  mean  on  the  part  of  Spinoza 
the  concession  of  anything  essential,  but  merely  the  broadening  of  his 
moral  point  of  view;  nobody  could  have  understood  better  that,  when 
the  hour  strikes,  sacrifice  (as  regarded  from  the  finite  point  of  view)  may 
have  to  be  absolute. 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  15 

from  reason"  (Prop.  LIII);  and  that  "Repentance  is  not  a 
virtue,  or  does  not  arise  from  reason;  but  he  who  repents  of 
an  action  is  doubly  wretched  or  infirm"  (Prop.  LIV),  lose 
much  of  their  apparently  paradoxical  character,  if  we  re 
member  that  in  each  case  Spinoza  is  speaking  of  mere  emo 
tions,  unregulated  by  reason,  which,  therefore,  according 
to  his  view,  belong  to  the  *  passive'  as  opposed  to  the  *  ac 
tive'  side  of  our  human  nature.  In  all  three  cases  he  recog 
nizes  that,  "as  men  seldom  live  under  the  guidance  of  rea 
son,"  these  passions  do  more  good  than  harm.1  Of  course 
this  is  not  to  say  that  the  philosopher  really  takes  the  con 
ventional  attitude  toward  these  distinctively  Christian 
emotions;  but  it  will  be  best  to  pass  on  at  once  to  what  will 
be  found  to  be  the  key  to  his  position. 

Many  misconceptions  of  Spinoza's  meaning,  at  this  the 
crucial  point  of  his  argument,  would  have  been  avoided,  if 
more  attention  had  been  paid  to  Proposition  LIX:  "To 
all  the  actions,  whereto  we  are  determined  by  emotion 
wherein  the  mind  is  passive,  we  can  be  determined  without 
passive  emotion  [dbsque  eo]  by  reason."  This  is  very 
badly  expressed  (in  the  ambiguous  original  text),  but  we 
need  not  be  in  doubt  as  to  the  philosopher's  meaning.  It 
will  be  remembered  that  Proposition  vu  of  this  Part  reads: 
"An  emotion  can  only  be  controlled  or  destroyed  by  another 
emotion  contrary  thereto,  and  with  more  power  for  con 
trolling  emotion."  Spinoza  never  forsakes  this  position, 
which  fact  differentiates  his  ethical  method  from  most  of 
later  ethical  rationalism.  At  first,  it  might  seem  to  commit 
him  to  some  form  of  determinism  of  the  purely  '  naturalis 
tic'  type,  which  would  rule  out  any  further  consideration 

1P.223. 

2  It  is  unfortunate  that  this  very  important  passage  should  have  been 
mistranslated  in  both  the  Elwes  and  the  White-Stirling  versions.  Elwes 
translates  the  last  clause:  "...  we  can  be  determined  without  emotion 
by  reason"  (Vol.  II,  p.  227);  the  White-Stirling  translation  reads:  "... 
we  may,  without  the  affect,  be  determined  by  reason"  (Second  edition, 
p.  228).  The  original  text  is  ambiguous  because  elliptical,  and  the  trans 
lations  criticised  are  grammatically  possible,  but  philosophically  they 
mean  the  opposite  of  what  Spinoza  certainly  meant. 


1 6  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

of  the  problem  of  moral  'freedom.'  But  this  is  not  the 
case:  even  in  the  'note'  appended  to  his  original  definition 
of  'emotion'  at  the  beginning  of  Part  III,  Spinoza  says: 
"If  we  can  be  the  adequate  cause  of  any  of  these  modifica 
tions  [of  body  and  mind,  involved  in  emotion],  I  then  call 
the  emotion  an  activity,  otherwise  I  call  it  a  passion,  or 
state  wherein  the  mind  is  passive."  1  In  other  words,  not 
all  'emotions'  are  'passions';  those  most  often  so  called  are 
doubtless  such,  and,  as  such,  are  due  mainly  to  'external 
causes'  (i.  e.,  they  constitute  our  'bondage');  but  the 
emotions  that  not  only  accompany,  but  also  help  to  sustain, 
our  rational  comprehension  of  things  in  their  essential  rela 
tions  are  not  'passive,' — rather  are  they  'activities'  and 
constitute  the  only  possible  dynamic  of  the  truly  moral  life. 
Our  'passions,'  in  Spinoza's  technical  sense  (where  we 
simply  give  way  to  strong  feeling),  are  not  only  signs  of  our 
'bondage,'  but  actual  links  in  our  chains,  while  our  'active' 
emotions,  already  bearing  witness  to  the  organizing  activity 
of  reason,  are  our  only  hope  of  'freedom'  and  our  only 
promise  of  the  'blessed  life.' 

Such,  then,  are  the  very  important  implications  of  Prop 
osition  LIX.  The  immediately  following  propositions  are 
consistent  enough  with  what  precedes  and  wholly  worthy 
of  consideration,  but  they  are  hardly  more  than  a  clumsy 
introduction  to  Proposition  LXVII:  "A  free  man  _thinks  of 
death  least  of  all  things;  and  his  wisdonTls^a"lneditation  not 
of  death  but  of  life."  2  Here,  then,  practically  at  the  end 
of  the  Part  of  the  Ethics  ostensibly  devoted  to  a  considera 
tion  of  "Human  Bondage,"  we  find  the  key-note  of  all  that 
is  best  and  most  profoundly  true  in  Spinoza's  ethical  theory. 
Perhaps  this  is  the  only  perfect  expression  of  "The  Ever 
lasting  Yea";  certainly  Carlyle's  famous  chapter  with  that 
title  in  his  best  known  book  is  shrill  and  inadequate  in  com 
parison. 

It  will  be  seen  that  Spinoza's  conception  of  moral  '  ac 
tivity'  or  'freedom,'  as  opposed  to  non-moral  or  immoral 
'passivity'  or  'bondage,'  has  already  been  indicated  in  a 
1  P.  130.  2P.  232. 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  17 

general  way  in  Part  IV,  "Of  Human  Bondage,  or  the 
Strength  of  the  Emotions."  It  is  equally  plain,  however, 
that  we  must  look  to  the  concluding  Part  V,  "Of  the  Power 
of  the  Understanding,  or  of  Human  Freedom,"  for  both 
the  further  development  and  the  vindication  of  Spinoza's 
ethical  theory.  The  philosopher's  mode  of  approach  to  his 
fundamental  problem  is  not  wholly  reassuring.  The  Preface 
is  mainly  devoted  to  a  rather  acute  criticism  of  Descartes' 
failure  to  reconcile  his  sweeping  indeterminism  with  the 
necessary  demands  of  the  mechanical  theory,  to  which  (as 
was  natural  for  its  author)  Descartes  himself  attributed  an 
almost  ontological  character.  But  Spinoza  begins  (Prop,  i) 
by  reasserting  what  I  have  ventured  to  call  the  hypothesis 
of  'psycho-physical  parallelism'  in  the  most  uncompromis 
ing  terms:  "Even  as  thoughts  and  the  ideas  of  things  are 
arranged  and  associated  in  the  mind,  so  are  the  modifica 
tions  of  body  or  the  images  of  things  precisely  in  the  same 
way  arranged  and  associated  in  the  body."  l  We  have 
already  seen  that,  taken  as  ultimately  true,  this  postulate 
conflicts  with  that  other  one  called  for  convenience  the 
postulate  of  'logical  parallelism'  (i.  <?.,  "The  order  and 
connection  of  ideas  is  the  same  as  the  order  and  connec 
tion  of  things");  for  plainly  it  is  one  thing  to  assert  the 
merely  factual  one  to  one  correspondence  of  certain  mental 
processes  and  their  physiological  (perhaps  ultimately  physi 
cal)  correlates,  and  quite  another  thing  to  assume  that  the 
world-order  is  a  quasi-logical  order  such  that,  in  the  last  re 
sort,  cause  and  effect  reduce  to  logical  ground  and  conse 
quent. 

It  is  equally  clear  that  one  cannot  at  the  same  time  and 
for  the  same  purpose  hold  to  the  postulate  of  '  psycho- 
physical  parallelism'  and  entertain  even  such  a  concep 
tion  of  moral  ( freedom'  as  Spinoza  himself  is  bound  to 
contend  for.  This  is  simply  another  confusion  of  two  dis 
tinct  problems  and  correspondingly  distinct  methods.  But 
almost  immediately  we  come  to  a  proposition  (Prop,  in) 
which  is  ambiguous  and  has  led  to  much  discussion:  "An 

1  P.  247. 


1 8  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

emotion,  which  is  a  passion,  ceases  to  be  a  passion,  as  soon 
as  we  form  a  clear  and  distinct  idea  thereof."  Here  we  must 
put  ourselves  in  Spinoza's  place,  if  we  would  understand 
him.  It  is,  of  course,  a  commonplace  of  modern  psychology 
that  it  is  difficult  to  deal  with  the  emotions  introspectively, 
since,  in  proportion  as  we  become  interested  in  the  scientific 
problem,  the  emotion  in  question  is  bound  to  disappear. 
It  is  fair  to  assume  that  Spinoza,  who  presumably  knew 
little  or  nothing  of  the  technical  difficulties  of  introspective 
psychology,  is  not  here  merely  turning  to  the  advantage  of 
ethics  a  law  of  our  mental  life  that  tends  to  thwart  psychol 
ogy.  On  the  other  hand,  nothing  can  be  said  for  the  popular 
misconception  that  Spinoza  wished  to  rule  out  or  transcend 
the  life  of  feeling  altogether  in  the  interest  of  moral  develop 
ment,  and  that,  in  this  proposition,  he  is  merely  pointing 
in  that  direction.  The  fact  seems  to  be  that,  although  the 
philosopher  has  just  reaffirmed  the  naturalistic  postulate 
of  '  psycho-physical  parallelism,'  the  distinction  which  he 
has  in  mind  is  essentially  ethical  rather  than  psychological. 
For  psychology,  as  for  science  in  general,  there  is  no  *  bet 
ter'  or  ' worse';  here  the  implied  distinction  is  that  between 
mere  'passion'  (non-moral  or  immoral)  and  that  'active' 
life  of  feeling  where  the  organizing  and  transforming  agency 
of  reason  is  to  be  found.  The  one  spells  'bondage,'  which, 
as  moral  beings,  we  are  trying  to  put  behind  us;  the  other, 
that  'freedom'  which  is  our  only  hope. 

The  'corollary'  to  this  proposition  helps  to  explain 
Spinoza's  meaning:  "An  emotion,  therefore,  becomes  more 
under  our  control,  and  the  mind  is  less  passive  in  respect  to 
it,  in  proportion  as  it  is  more  known  to  us."  Robbed  of 
their  mystery  and  seen  in  their  proper  context,  even  our 
strongest  passions  cease  to  be  mere  'passions';  and,  speak 
ing  generally,  our  emotional  life  is  capable  of  becoming 
progressively  organized,  and  therefore  'active,'  in  pro 
portion  as  we  understand  better  our  relations  to  our  fellow 
men  and  to  the  world-order  as  a  whole.  As  Spinoza  remarks 
in  the  'note'  to  the  next  proposition,  "all  appetites  or 
desires  are  only  passions,  in  so  far  as  they  spring  from  in- 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  19 

adequate  ideas;  the  same  results  are  accredited  to  virtue, 
when  they  are  aroused  or  generated  by  adequate  ideas."  1 
And  he  characteristically  adds  (Prop,  vi) :  "The  mind  has 
greater  power  over  the  emotions  and  is  less  subject  thereto, 
in  so  far  as  it  understands  all  things  as  necessary."  2 

After  attempting  to  indicate  more  in  detail  the  principles 
involved  in  this  progressive  organization  of  the  emotions, 
Spinoza  proceeds  to  expound  his  conception  of  the  ultimate 
synthesis.  Proposition  xv  reads:  "He  who  clearly  and 
distinctly  understands  himself  and  his  emotions  loves  God, 
and  so  much  the  more  in  proportion  as  he  more  understands 
himself  and  his  emotions."  3  And  the  following  proposition 
reads:  "This  love  towards  God  must  hold  the  chief  place 
in  the  mind."  While  this  ideal  of  'the  intellectual  love  of 
God/  taken  as  representing  our  supreme  duty  and,  at  the 
same  time,  as  pointing  the  only  way  to  the  '  blessed  life,' 
presents  many  difficulties,  we  are  not  here  primarily  con 
cerned  with  the  metaphysical  issues  involved  and  still  less 
with  their  bearing  upon  popular  religion.  It  must  be  frankly 
admitted  that  this  apparent  identification  of  the  intellectual 
and  the  religious  experience,  when  both  are  taken  at  their 
highest,  hardly  corresponds  to  any  easily  recognizable 
trend  of  recent  thought.4  Certain  of  the  more  ambitious 

*  P.  249. 

2  P.  250.     It  will  be  remembered  that  there  is  a  serious  ambiguity  in 
Spinoza's  conception  of  'necessity,'   but   here   he   need  not  necessarily 
be  understood  as  meaning  more  than  that  the  world  may  and  must  be 
regarded  as  a  knowable  order. 

3  R  2?5'. 

4  In  his  interesting  address  on  "The  Real  University,"  delivered  at  the 

opening  of  Columbia  University  last  autumn  and  published  in  the  Educa 
tional  Review,  November,  1916,  Professor  Seligman  says:  "To  many,  .  .  . 
especially  in  this  audience,  the  only  church  is  the  laboratory;  the  only 
religion  is  science."  (P.  327.)  This  passing  remark  is  quoted,  not  be 
cause  it  really  indicates  the  speaker's  own  point  of  view  (for  he  suggests 
the  necessary  qualifications),  but  because  it  illustrates  a  popular  use  of 
language  that  is  rather  misleading  unless  it  is  clearly  recognized  as  figura 
tive.  Of  course  an  investigator  in  physics  or  chemistry  might  take  a 
personal  attitude  of  self-devotion,  etc.,  toward  his  science  that  would 
have  something  in  common  with  what  is  ordinarily  meant  by  the  religious 


20  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

flights  of  Absolute  Idealism  might  perhaps  be  cited  as  a 
contemporary  parallel,  but  the  relevance  of  the  comparison 
would  largely  disappear  when  the  necessary  qualifications 
were  made.1  But,  on  the  other  hand,  what  may  well  seem 
foreign  and  dubious  to  us  doubtless  seemed  plainly  inevitable 
to  Spinoza :  no  attempt  at  an  ultimate  solution  of  the  ethico- 
religious  problem  could  have  seemed  to  him  more  in  accord 
with  his  general  standpoint  and  method.  The  fatal  difficulty 
is  that  his  characteristic  standpoint  and  method  involved 
that  very  confusion  of  categories  to  an  examination  of 
which  this  article  has  been  devoted. 

We  must  clearly  recognize  that,  while  Spinoza  avoided 
the  highly  abstract  ethical  rationalism  that  was  soon  to  be 
developed,  and  that  was  bound  sooner  or  later  to  put  ra 
tionalism  itself  at  a  needless  disadvantage  as  a  possible 
ethical  method,  he  was,  after  all,  a  dogmatic  rationalist. 

attitude;  at  the  same  time,  the  fact  remains  that  scientific  procedure  itself 
is  as  impersonal  as  the  religious  experience  proper  is  bound  to  be  personal 
(certain  of  William  James's  more  paradoxical  arguments  to  the  contrary 
notwithstanding).  That  anything  in  our  experience  can  be  merely  'per 
sonal'  or  merely  '  impersonal,'  the  writer  would,  of  course,  be  the  first 
to  deny.  So  much  for  the  figure  of  speech;  if,  on  the  other  hand,  it  were 
conceivable  that  a  scientific  investigator  should  make  a  'religion'  of 
science  to  the  extent  of  recognizing  no  human  obligations  or  minimum 
limits  of  common  decency,  he  would  naturally  be  shut  up, — the  question 
whether  he  were  criminal  or  merely  insane,  hard  perhaps  to  settle,  would 
after  all  be  a  relatively  academic  one.  Perhaps  more  relevant  to  the 
main  discussion  is  the  remark  of  Carlyle  that  "the  man  who  had  mas 
tered  the  first  forty-seven  propositions  of  Euclid  stood  nearer  to  God 
than  he  had  done  before."  (Quoted  by  John  Nichol  in  his  volume  on 
Carlyle,  "English  Men  of  Letters"  series,  p.  20.)  If  Carlyle  had  really 
meant  this  and  lived  up  to  it,  he  would  have  been  elucidating  Spinoza's 
meaning  rather  than  propounding  a  paradox. 

1  There  is  no  surer  way  of  misunderstanding  Spinoza  than  by  assuming 
that  he  was  a  premature  Absolute  Idealist.  He  was  an  Absolutist,  of 
course,  but  a  good  deal  of  water  flowed  under  the  philosophical  bridge 
during  the  next  century  and  a  quarter,  or  more.  Lest  this  be  thought  a 
criticism  in  particular  of  Mr.  Joachim's  already  classic  Study  of  the  Ethics 
of  Spinoza  (1901),  the  writer  begs  to  admit  that  he  has  learned  as  much 
from  this  admirable  book,  which  he  cannot  follow  in  all  respects,  as  from 
any  one  commentary. 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  21 

His  earlier  statements  as  to  the  inevitable  relativity  of 
moral  conceptions  must  not  be  allowed  to  confuse  us  on  this 
point;  for  in  the  passages  referred  to  he  was  really  insisting 
upon  the  *  necessity'  of  the  world-order  from  the  point  of 
view  of  mechanism,  provisionally  assumed  as  an  ultimate 
account  of  the  structure  of  the  world  as  knowable.  Here, 
when  discussing  the  moral  problem,  he  has  unconsciously, 
if  not  consciously,  shifted  his  point  of  view.  The  moral 
order  is  still  regarded  as,  in  a  sense,  'necessary,'  but  the 
' necessity'  contended  for  is  moral  and  not  physical  or 
quasi-physical  necessity.  Even  when  Spinoza  was  about 
to  consider  "Human  Bondage,"  the  Good,  it  will  be  remem 
bered,  was  defined  as  "that  which  we  certainly  know  to  be 
useful  to  us,"  while  evil  was  correspondingly  defined  as 
"that  which  we  certainly  know  to  be  a  hindrance  to  us  in 
the  attainment  of  any  good."  What  we  call  'early  ra 
tionalism'  was  for  Spinoza  simply  another  name  for  philoso 
phy  itself;  and  he  naturally  assumed  that  the  rationalistic 
method  was  as  applicable  to  the  problems  of  ethics  as  to 
those  of  metaphysics.  The  real  alternatives  for  him  were 
ethical  rationalism  of  the  most  thoroughgoing  type  and 
theological  superstition,  which  he  regarded  as  the  enemy 
to  be  defeated  at  all  hazards.  This  explains  why  he  so 
readily  takes  refuge  in  what  might  seem  the  partly  mystical 
conception  of  'the  intellectual  love  of  God.'  For  him  the 
only  'free'  or  'active,'  and  therefore  ethically  or  reli 
giously  worthy,  'love  of  God'  must  needs  be  this  'intel 
lectual  love,'  since  all  other  love  for  Him  could  only  be  a 
'passion,'  ultimately  due  to  superstition.  That  religion 
could  really  involve  a  synthesis  of  experience  on  a  higher 
plane  than  that  of  our  emotions  progressively  purified  in 
proportion  to  our  ever-advancing  intellectual  comprehen 
sion  of  the  world  as  a  whole,  he  does  not  seem  to  recognize 
as  a  possibility. 

It  might  seem  that  we  have  now  considered,  however 
cursorily,  all  that  properly  comes  within  the  scope  of  our 
proposed  examination  of  'the  confusion  of  categories'  in 
1  Definitions  I  and  II,  Part  IV,  p.  190. 


Wv 


22  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 


Spinoza's  Ethics.  At  the  same  time,  it  would  perhaps  be 
thought  an  evasion,  if  one  should  omit  all  mention  of  the 
undoubted  difficulties  involved  in  the  philosopher's  attempt, 
at  the  very  end  of  the  Ethics,  to  deal  with  the  'eternity' 
of  the  human  mind.  Even  the  little  that  really  need  be  said 
here  requires  a  word  of  introduction.  We  are  not  directly 
concerned  with  the  strictly  metaphysical  difficulties  in 
volved  in  Spinoza's  conception  of  'eternity,'  including,  as 
these  do,  not  only  the  problem  as  to  the  place  of  time,  but 
also  that  as  to  the  meaning  of  'reality,'  in  his  system;  and 
still  less  are  we  concerned  with  any  speculation  as  to  the 
possible  reconcilement  of  Spinoza's  apparent  solution  with 
what  seems  really  fundamental  in  religion  itself,  as  opposed 
to  various  forms  of  more  or  less  popular  theology.  The  ques 
tion  before  us  is  wholly  one  as  to  categories  or  methods  em 
ployed  and  their  possible  confusion. 

From  this  point  of  view,  the  difficulty  for  the  technical 
student  of  philosophy  is  almost  the  opposite  of  that  of 
common-sense.  An  intelligent  student  of  the  world's  lit 
erature,  reading  the  Ethics  as  a  classic,  much  as  he  might 
read  Plato's  Dialogues,  would  be  likely  to  feel  that  there  was 
something  rather  perfunctory  in  Spinoza's  attempt  to  vin 
dicate  the  'eternity'  of  the  human  mind,  after  insisting  so 
strongly  upon  the  necessary  connection  between  mind  and 
body  as  to  make  the  belief  in  any  recognizable  form  of  im 
mortality  the  height  of  unreason.  But  what  appears  as  a 
paradox  or  worse  to  common-sense  must  be  recognized  by 
the  serious  student  of  philosophy  as  rather  a  fairly  logical 
corollary  from  Spinoza's  fundamental  assumptions,  though 
a  corollary  which  very  strongly  accentuates  some  of  the 
essential  difficulties  of  his  system.  No  real  student  of  the 
history  of  philosophy  need  be  reminded  that  Spinoza's  whole 
ideal  is  to  view  things  sub  specie  czternitatis ;  but  in  exactly 
what  sense  the  philosopher  proposes  to  transcend  the  tem 
poral  standpoint  is  difficult,  if  not  impossible,  to  determine. 
His  over-emphasis  of  the  mathematical  method,  as  he  mis 
conceives  it,  is  rather  a  defect  to  be  excused  than  a  possible 
means  of  vindicating  his  characteristic,  if  hopelessly  vague, 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  23 

position.  Everything  that  ' necessarily'  follows  from  the 
'essence'  of  God  or  Nature,  must  be  conceived  as  having 
a  non-temporal  significance  and  reality.  This  may  seem 
plausible  as  a  general  statement;  but,  unfortunately,  we 
have  found  that  *  necessity'  is  a  very  ambiguous  term  in 
Spinoza's  philosophy:  we  cannot  afford  to  lump  together 
logical,  ontological,  physical,  and  moral  'necessity,'  if  we 
would  make  any  pretence  to  exact  thinking.  The  underlying 
assumption  seems  to  be  that  reality  as  a  whole  is  essentially 
a  logical  or  quasi-logical  order,  and  that,  therefore,  to  under 
stand  this  order  in  its  true  nature  is  so  far  forth  to  transcend 
the  temporal  point  of  view.  In  spite  of  the  fascination  that 
more  sophisticated  versions  of  this  ultra-logical  assumption 
still  seem  to  have  for  a  certain  type  of  mind,  one  must  protest 
that  this  was  the  very  fallacy  that  Hume,  consciously  or 
unconsciously,  made  forever  impossible  for  his  more  dis 
cerning  successors.  And  that  is  why  philosophy  has  never 
been  easy  since  Hume  published  his  Treatise  of  Human 
Nature  (1739-40).  For  those  who  naturally  sympathize  with 
what  they  regard  as  Spinoza's  larger  purpose,  the  temptation 
is  great  to  over-interpret  his  meaning  in  terms  of  Absolute 
Idealism  and  invoke  on  his  behalf  arguments  which  one  may 
fairly  assume  the  philosopher  himself  would  not  even  have 
understood. 

Here,  indeed,  we  find  the  ultimate  conflict  between  the 
postulates  of  'logical  parallelism'  and  'psycho-physical 
parallelism.'  The  former  is,  of  course,  fundamental  for 
Spinoza's  thinking  as  a  whole,  though  so  vague  as  almost 
inevitably  to  lead  to  inconsistent  applications.  This  postu 
late,  it  should  be  observed,  is  ambiguous  as  to  the  significance 
of  time  for  the  system,  though  pointing  in  the  direction  of 
the  non-temporal  or  'eternal.'  On  the  other  hand,  it  is 
difficult  to  assign  any  definite  meaning  to  the  postulate  of 
'psycho-physical  parallelism'  that  does  not  take  time  at  its 
face  value.  And  Spinoza  clearly  recognizes  that,  from  this 
latter  point  of  view,  the  'eternity'  of  the  mind  is  not  even 
a  problem.  Proposition  xxi  is  perfectly  explicit  on  this 
point:  "The  mind  can  only  imagine  anything,  or  remember 


24  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

what  is  past,  while  the  body  endures."  1  The  wording  of 
Proposition  xxm,  on  the  other  hand,  is  rather  unfortunate; 
Spinoza  says:  "The  human  mind  cannot  be  absolutely 
destroyed  with  the  body,  but  there  remains  of  it  some 
thing  which  is  eternal."  Since  'eternity,'  as  understood  by 
Spinoza,  has  no  reference  to  time,  but  only  to  the  ultimate 
'necessary'  order,  this  concession  to  the  ordinary  use  of 
language  is  likely  to  be  misleading. 

But,  while  we  find  here  an  evident  confusion  of  categories, 
there  is  no  greater  difficulty  in  understanding  the  philos 
opher's  probable  meaning  than  there  always  is  when  he 
attempts  to  show  the  relation  of  the  temporal  to  the  'eter 
nal.'  For  (i)  everything  whatever  has  its  'eternal'  as  well 
as  its  temporal  aspect:  in  this  respect,  the  most  insignificant  2 
thing  or  event  that  could  be  mentioned  is  'eternal'  as  well 
as  the  individual  mind.  But  (2),  as  Spinoza  says  in  the 
rather  confused  'note'  to  this  proposition, — after  recog 
nizing  the  impossibility  of  anything  like  the  mythical  'mem 
ory'  of  'pre-existence,' — "Notwithstanding,  we  feel  and 
know  that  we  are  eternal.  For  the  mind  feels  those  things 
that  it  conceives  by  understanding,  no  less  than  those  things 
that  it  remembers.  For  the  eyes  of  the  mind,  whereby  it 
sees  and  observes  things,  are  none  other  than  proofs."  3  In 
other  words,  the  very  fact  that  the  mind  is  capable  of  rec 
ognizing  non-temporal,  i.  e.,  logical  'necessity,'  makes  it 
certain  that  the  mind  itself  is  'eternal'  in  the  same  non- 
temporal  sense.  In  this  form,  the  argument  seems  not  only 
inconclusive,  but  irrelevant.4 

1  P.  259. 

2  Of  course  nothing,  in  the  last  resort,  can  be  regarded  as  'insignificant' 
for  a  closed  system  where  everything  is  'necessary.'    We  have  already 
seen  reason  to  doubt,  however,  that  Spinoza  consistently  keeps  to  the 
idea  of  a  '  closed  system '  in  the  original  sense.  3  P.  260. 

4  Nineteenth  century  Idealism  argued,  with  considerable  force,  that 
even  our  recognition  of  temporal  succession  involved  something  more 
than,  and  different  from,  a  mere  succession  of  'states  of  consciousness' 
on  our  part;  here,  on  the  other  hand,  Spinoza  seems  to  argue  that  the 
mind  must  be  'eternal,'  in  the  sense  that  logical  and  mathematical  truths 
are  'eternal,'  since  otherwise  it  could  not  comprehend  such  truths. 


SPINOZA'S  CONFUSION  OF  CATEGORIES  25 

And  yet  Spinoza's  intuitions  seem  to  have  been  more 
sound,  at  any  rate,  than  his  logical  procedure.  Perhaps  the 
religious  side  of  his  philosophy  could  be  partly  characterized 
by  the  words  that  Professor  A.  C.  Bradley  employs  in  his 
Oxford  Lectures  on  Poetry,  when  attempting  to  define  the 
better  side  of  Wordsworth's  optimism:  "The  gulf  which 
for  Byron  and  Shelley  yawned  between  the  real  and  the 
ideal,  had  no  existence  for  him.  For  him  the  ideal  was  real 
ized,  and  Utopia  a  country  which  he  saw  every  day,  and 
which,  he  thought,  every  man  might  see  who  did  not  strive, 
nor  cry,  nor  rebel,  but  opened  his  heart  in  love  and  thankful 
ness  to  sweet  influences  as  universal  and  perpetual  as  the 
air."  l  In  other  words,  the  ideal  does  not  merely  point  to 
an  unknown  future;  it  involves  also  an  ( eternal'  present.2 
Not  only  is  'the  Kingdom  of  Heaven'  'within  us':  it  is 
'eternally'  here  and  now,  though  the  extreme  of  temporal 
evil  may  obscure  its  presence.  The  concluding  proposition 
of  the  Ethics  is  one  of  the  best  of  commentaries:  "Blessed 
ness  is  not  the  reward  of  virtue,  but  virtue  itself;  neither  do 
we  rejoice  therein,  because  we  control  our  lusts,  but,  con 
trariwise,  because  we  rejoice  therein,  we  are  able  to  control 
our  lusts." 

1  P.  107. 

2  The  immense  difference,  on  the  whole,  between  Spinoza's  characteris 
tic  position  and  that  of  Wordsworth  hardly  needs  to  be  mentioned:  the 
mystical  or  semi-mystical   apprehension  of  the  'eternal'  realization  of 
the  ideal  can  only  follow  the  most  long  sustained  use  of  reason  for  Spinoza, 
while  for  Wordsworth  it  must  come  as  a  result  of  that  'wise  passiveness' 
which  he  delighted  to  defend. 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA 
KATHERINE  EVERETT  GILBERT 

IN  spite  of  the  fact  that  some  of  the  most  important 
recent  commentaries  on  Spinoza  have  attributed  to  him  an 
almost  modern  concreteness,  Hegel's  interpretation  of 
Spinoza  as  essentially  an  Eleatic  is  still  commonly  accepted. 
When  his  philosophy  is  classified  or  briefly  summarized, 
the  unprofitable  theory  of  substance  is  likely  to  be  empha 
sized.  The  term  Spinozistic  has  even  become  a  convenient 
designation  of  metaphysical  abstractness  wherever  found. 
For  example,  when  Professor  Pringle-Pattison  wishes  to 
distinguish  between  the  abstract  and  concrete  phases  of 
Mr.  Bradley's  theory  of  reality,  he  characterizes  them  as 
the  Spinozistic  and  Hegelian  phases  respectively.  Since  it 
was  Hegel  who,  by  the  extent  and  consistency  of  his  criticism 
and  from  the  vantage-ground  of  his  own  more  synthetic 
theory,  first  stamped  Spinozism  as  an  abstract  ontology, 
it  is  worth  while  examining  his  view  in  some  detail  if  we  wish 
to  determine  the  justice  of  the  entire  interpretation. 

In  one  important  respect  Hegel  found  himself  in  agree 
ment  with  Spinoza.  He  believed  that  Spinoza  had  grasped 
correctly  the  first  stage  of  a  true  philosophical  procedure, 
for  all  valid  philosophy  must  begin,  as  Spinoza  began,  with 
the  doctrine  of  the  essential  unity  of  the  world  and  the 
relative  unreality  of  perceived  things.  We  must  abandon 
the  common  uncritical  assumption  that  things  are  as  they 
in  the  first  instance  seem,  if  we  hope  to  learn  the  truth  about 
reality.  "The  soul  must  commence  by  bathing  in  this  ether 
of  the  One  Substance,  in  which  all  that  man  has  held  as 
true  has  disappeared;  this  negation  of  all  that  is  particular, 
to  which  every  philosopher  must  have  come,  is  the  libera 
tion  of  the  mind  and  its  absolute  foundation."  l 

1  Hegel,  Lectures  on  the  History  of  Philosophy,  tr.  by  Haldane,  Vol.  Ill, 
pp.  257!.;  see  also  The  Logic  of  Hegel,  tr.  by  Wallace,  2d  ed.,  pp.  is8f. 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA  27 

But  just  as  a  right  beginning, — the  renunciation  of  all  that 
is  determinate  and  particular  and  the  restricting  himself 
to  the  One, — "constitutes  the  grandeur  of  Spinoza's  manner 
of  thought,"  l  so  the  inability  to  move  beyond  this  starting- 
point  is  its  weakness.  The  One  must,  indeed,  sustain  all 
that  is  real  by  being  its  foundation  and  essence,  but  it  must 
do  more  than  this;  it  must  change  itself  into  divergent  forms 
and  move  in  a  process  of  development.  The  category  of 
substance  should  be  transmuted  and  exalted  into  the  cate 
gory  of  subject,  spirit,  or  person;  the  clue  to  ultimate  reality 
is  the  human  consciousness.  But  as  it  is,  Hegel  finds  the 
Spinozistic  substance  "rigid,"  "unworkable,"  "unyielding," 
"motionless."  He  contrasts  with  it  Boehme's  conception 
of  the  unity  of  the  Father  as  "an  inward  spring  and  fermen 
tation,"  2  and  his  "originating  spirits"  which  "energize 
and  expand  in  one  another."  3  "Each  spirit  in  the  seven 
spirits  of  God  is  pregnant  with  all  seven."  4 

The  dead  and  abstract  character  of  substance  implies  a 
complementary  abstractness  in  the  particulars  of  the  finite 
world.  They  are  a  "bare  finite  and  adventitious  congeries 
of  existence."  They  lie  about  as  sheep  having  no  shepherd. 
Substance  lacks  any  principle  of  motion  or  individuation, 
and  cannot  show  itself,  therefore,  as  the  truth  and  being  of 
things.  Since  Spinoza  cannot  deduce  them  from  his  first 
principle,  he  is  forced  to  assume  them  as  immediately  given 
in  experience.5  Strictly,  therefore,  his  individual  things  \ 
are  mere  nothings,  because  they  cannot  be  exhibited  as 
determinations  of  that  which  can  alone  give  them  a  degree 
of  substantiality.  This  annihilation  of  the  concrete  world 
is  the  logical  implication  of  the  Spinozistic  doctrine  that  all 
determination  is  negation. 

Substance  is  an  empty  and  independent  universal;  things 
are  empty  and  independent  particulars;  the  connection 
between  them  can  only  be  one  of  absolute  divergence  or, 
in  the  attempt  to  combine  them,  absolute  identification. 

1  History  of  Philosophy,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  258. 

2  Ibid.,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  202.  *  7^.,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  202. 

3  Ibid.,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  288.  5  /^.,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  289. 


28  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

Considered  as  entities,  things  are  completely  separated 
from  substance;  that  is,  they  are  without  being;  considered 
as  modes  of  substance,  they  are  completely  identified  with 
it  and  lose  their  individuality;  they  are  "cast  down  into 
this  abyss  of  annihilation."  l 

There  can  be  little  doubt,  I  think,  that  in  this  criticism 
Hegel  has  set  clearly  in  the  light  the  weak  side  of  Spinoza's 
philosophy.  In  the  abstract  ontology  of  Part  I  2  of  the 
Ethics,  Spinoza  fails  to  demonstrate  any  organic  connection 
between  the  ultimate  reality  of  substance  and  the  concrete 
world  of  things.  But  of  course  a  failure  in  achievement 
does  not  necessarily  involve  a  corresponding  inadequacy 
in  theoretical  ideal.  To  Hegel's  reiterated  criticism,-— 
that  Spinoza  merely  assumes  individual  determinations  and 
does  not  deduce  them  from  substance, — it  may  be  replied 
that  Spinoza  at  least  repeatedly  asserts  the  existence  of  such 
a  development  and  sequence.  He  says,  for  example,  that 
"from  the  necessity  of  the  divine  nature  must  follow  an 
infinite  number  of  things  in  infinite  ways,"  3  or,  as  he  para 
phrases  himself  a  few  lines  below,  "From  God's  supreme 
power,  or  infinite  nature  ...  all  things  have  necessarily 
flowed  forth;"  4  and  he  characterizes  God  ajs  the  "emana- 
tive,"  "productive,"  "active,"  or  "operating"  cause  of  all 
his  works.5  Indeed,  Spinoza  has  seemed  to  some  critics 
to  insist  as  strongly  upon  the  doctrine  of  the  evolution  or 
emanation  of  God's  nature  as  upon  the  affirmative  character 
of  substance.6  This  is  not  so  slight  a  retort  as  might  be  at 

1  History  of  Philosophy,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  288. 

2  It  was  this  part  of  the  Ethics  which  chiefly  occupied  Hegel.    He  says 
that  all  Spinozism  is  summed  up  in  the  first  seven  definitions.     Ibid., 
Vol.  Ill,  p.  263. 

3  Ethics,  Pt.  I,  Prop,  xvi;  p.  59.    Page  references  to  Spinoza's  writings, 
unless  otherwise  specified,  are  to  Elwes'  translation  of  the  '  Chief  Works,' 
Vol.  II. 

4  Ibid.,  Pt.  I,  Prop,  xvii,  note;  pp.  6of. 

5  Short  Treatise,  tr.  by  Wolf,  p.  41. 

6  For  example,  Lovejoy,  "The  Dialectic  of  Bruno  and  Spinoza,"  Uni 
versity  of  California  Publications:  Philosophy,  Vol.  I,  pp.  I4iff.     Saisset 
says  that  the  sixteenth  proposition,  quoted  above,  is  the  whole  of  Spino 
zism;  Introduction  critique  aux  ceuvres  de  Spinoza,  1860,  pp.  38f. 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA  29 

first  supposed,  for  it  is  doubtful  whether,  even  with  Hegel's 
emendation,  Spinoza  could  do  much  more  than  assert  that 
the  development  was  logically  bound  to  occur,  if  he  were 
to  begin  with  the  type  of  principle  which  he  actually  em 
ployed.  Spinoza's  original  premise  was  fatal  to  any  kind 
of  concrete  conclusion.  But  this  is  just  the  point  that  Hegel 
missed.  Indeed,  in  spite  of  the  important  differences  in 
point  of  view,  there  is  an  interesting  coincidence  in  the 
logical  demands  of  the  two  rationalists  which  we  shall  pro 
ceed  to  examine. 

Hegel,  as  we  noticed,  approved  of  Spinoza's  initial  stand 
point.  That  there  is  one  correct  way  to  begin  philosophical 
speculation,  and  that  that  way  is  by  "  bathing  in  the  ether 
of  the  One  Substance  and  negating  all  that  is  particular," 
both  philosophers  agree.  As  Spinoza's  Ethics  begins  with 
the  definition  of  substance,  Hegel's  dialectical  unfolding  of 
the  pure  logical  idea  begins  with  "thought  in  its  merest 
indeterminateness,  .  .  .  the  original  featurelessness  which 
precedes  all  definite  character  and  is  the  very  first  of  all."  1 
Through  a  process  which  is  supposed  to  express  the  inherent 
nature  of  reason,  everything  evolves  for  Hegel  from  this 
simple  beginning.  The  category  of  being  realizes  itself  in  a 
comprehensive  system  of  ideas  which  in  some  sense  was  all 
implicit  in  the  origin.  The  objection  that  there  are  after  all 
important  differences  in  the  two  methods  is  not  precisely 
relevant.  It  is  true  that  for  Spinoza  reality  was  postulated 
in  its  completeness  in  the  initial  idea  of  substance,  while  for 
Hegel  the  largest  part  of  reality  was  yet  to  appear  when  the 
first  thought  was  given.  But  the  point  is  that,  for  both, 
pure  thought  may  properly  begin  with  an  empty  category. 
There  is  divergence  too  in  their  theory  of  deduction.  For 
Spinoza  the  succession  of  essences  that  flows  from  the 
fountain-head  of  being  does  not  involve  any  idea  of  increase 
or  necessary  completion,  but  rather  a  diminution  or  falling 
away;  for  Hegel  the  rational  process  is  the  supplying  of  the 
indispensable  implications  of  the  original  idea:  but  for  both 
the  sequence  of  thought  is  a  deduction  to  this  extent,  that 
1  Logic,  tr.  by  Wallace,  p.  159. 


30  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  particular  is  evolved  in  a  process  of  the  necessary  forma 
tion  of  concepts.  It  is  not  relevant,  in  the  second  place,  to 
say  that  the  Logic  is  part  of  a  larger  work  and  its  standpoint 
deliberately  abstract;  its  scheme  is  supposed  to  be  identical 
with  that  of  actual  intellectual  development.  Hegel  doubt 
less  transcended  his  abstractness  in  his  numerous  discussions 
of  definite  problems, — of  the  state,  the  family,  history,  and 
religion, — but  it  is  here  a  question  of  the  logical  ideal  stated 
abstractly.  Spinoza,  too,  gave  content  to  substance  and  in 
dividuality  to  man  when  he  was  investigating  the  problems 
of  the  moral  life,  as  we  shall  presently  see. 

Now  in  opposition  to  Hegel  it  may,  I  think,  be  maintained 
that  it  was  Spinoza's  preoccupation  with  a  right  beginning 
and  an  infallible  deduction,  and  his  renunciation  of  partic 
ularity,  which  were  important  causes  of  that  very  abstract- 
ness  to  which  Hegel  objected.  The  assumption,  characteris 
tic  of  early  rationalism,  that  there  was  only  one  correct 
beginning  and  one  correct  procedure  for  thought,  forced  him 
to  seek  some  idea  which  was  everywhere  relevant  and  there 
fore  relevant  exactly  nowhere.  Substance  was  posited  in  the 
attempt  to  give  once  for  all  the  ultimate  ground  of  all  events, 
regardless  of  reference  to  particular  purposes.  It  is  a  com 
monplace  of  modern  logic  that  a  cause  or  ground  cannot  be 
thus  an  unconditioned  condition  but  must  be  ideologically 
determined;  that  is,  its  significance  and  scope  are  restricted 
by  the  significance  and  scope  of  the  facts  under  investigation. 
The  fruitfulness  of  scientific  endeavor  has  resulted  in  large 
measure  from  the  restriction  of  the  attempt,  and  the  an 
nihilation  of  limitation  is  as  fatal  to  philosophy  as  to 
science. 

Let  us  turn  from  Hegel's  favorable  to  his  unfavorable 
criticism.  Spinoza  began  right,  Hegel  says,  but  he  failed  to 
follow  his  first  principle  out  into  its  determinations.  How 
did  Hegel  propose  to  transform  Spinozism  to  make  it  a  true 
philosophy?  He  would  supply  a  demonstration  of  the  modus 
operandi  by  which  necessary  unity  becomes  free  individual 
ity.  The  abstract  point  of  view  of  the  whole  is  a  legitimate 
beginning;  the  defect  consists  in  not  showing  how  the  whole 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA  31 

moves  from  stage  to  stage  in  a  process  of  self-realization. 
The  instability  and  imperfection  of  the  abstract  category  is 
the  notion  which  Spinoza  lacked.  But  by  both  Spinoza  and 
Hegel  categories  are  treated  as  if  they  had  an  inherent  and 
absolute  potency.  Thought  in  the  abstract  has  its  own  law 
of  progression,  whether,  as  for  Spinoza,  this  law  is  taken 
from  the  analogy  of  geometry,  or,  as  for  Hegel,  it  is  a  dialectic 
with  its  thesis,  antithesis,  and  synthesis;  the  thinking  of 
particular  human  beings  may  acquiesce  in  or  penetrate  to 
"that  core  of  truth  which,  originally  produced  and  producing 
itself,  .  .  .  has  become  the  world,  the  inward  and  outward 
world,  of  consciousness,"  1  but  it  can  scarcely  shape  it  or  alter 
its  significance.  Spinoza  speaks  of  the  "happy  chance" 
by  which  some  person  might  fall  into  the  correct  order  at  the 
outset  of  his  reflection,  and  the  development  of  rationality 
is  for  Hegel  the  evolution  of  the  Absolute  Idea  in  itself,  to 
itself,  and  for  itself. 

Upon  this  special  point,  then,  it  would  seem  that  criticism 
may  be  directed  at  both  Spinoza  and  Hegel.  The  laws  of 
thought  cannot  be  reduced  to  a  single  order  of  categories  or 
truths.  Concepts  are  not  powers,  independent  of  their  use 
in  a  specific  investigation.  Their  satisfactoriness  and  im 
portance  depend  on  their  capacity  to  meet  a  particular  in 
tellectual  need;  their  function  is  not  absolutely  but  relatively 
defined.  In  so  far  as  Hegel  pointed  out  the  unfruitfulness  of 
the  conception  of  substance,  he  was  doubtless  right;  but  in 
so  far  as  he  would  substitute  for  substance  some  other  ab 
solute  or  universal  which  should  furnish  an  ideal  method  of 
thought,  he  was  merely  advocating  one  kind  of  rationalism, 
even  if  a  better  kind,  in  place  of  another.  How  speculation 
can  start  with  an  absolute  whole,  devoid  of  determination, 
and  reach  determination  must  always  remain  a  problem. 
The  point  may  perhaps  be  made  more  vivid  by  an  analogy. 
The  human  figure  represented  in  a  picture  has  more  points 
of  resemblance  with  a  living  being  than  the  background 

1  Logic,  tr.  by  Wallace,  p.  9. 

2  On  the  Improvement  of  the  Understanding,  p.  16.    The  original  reads 
fato  quodam. 


32  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

of  a  picture,  and  so  the  concept  of  spirit  may  designate 
more  exactly  than  the  concept  of  substance  the  con 
crete  life  of  thought;  but  it  is  no  more  possible  to  elicit 
the  functions  of  a  living  being  from  the  representation 
of  a  human  figure  than  from  the  background,  and  simi 
larly  the  concept  of  spirit,  so  long  as  it  is  uninformed 
with  the  determinations  of  experience,  cannot  any  more 
than  substance  give  birth  to  a  living  process  of  think 
ing. 

The  most  interesting  consequence  of  Hegel's  own  point  of 
view  for  his  criticism  of  Spinoza  is  yet  to  appear.  Hegel  not 
only  found  abstractness  in  Spinoza  where  it  actually  existed, 
but,  because  of  his  own  impatience  with  an  empirical  be 
ginning,  he  found  it  where  it  was  at  least  partially  superseded 
by  concreteness.  In  an  interesting  passage  in  his  Philosophy 
of  Religion  l  he  says  that  Spinoza  did  not  attempt  any  con 
crete  science  except  ethics,  and  that  in  that  he  failed  because 
its  principles,  content,  and  starting-point  were  taken  from 
experience  and  not  deduced  from  that  substance  which  should 
have  been  its  moving  principle  and  method.  It  starts  with 
what  is  perceived  by  the  senses,  Hegel  complains,  and  so, 
although  it  may  be  logical  enough  in  itself,  it  is  a  mere  "  or 
dinary  science,"  lacking  any  unifying  principle.  If  Spinoza 
had  only  conceived  of  God  as  a  subject  or  creator  instead  of 
as  a  necessary  foundation,  human  virtue  might  have  been 
exhibited  as  a  high  manifestation  of  his  power.  But  nature 
and  human  life  are  necessarily  abstract  if  God  is  abstract; 
they  must  be  the  other  incomplete,  unrelated  half  of  the 
universe.  They  are  pure  appearance,  as  God  is  pure  being. 
Finite  things  have  a  false  individuality  because  they  are 
external  to  substance;  and  they  must  be  external,  because 
the  metaphysical  system  has  not  shown  them  as  necessary 
moments  in  an  evolution.  In  this  passage  Hegel  does  not 
seem  to  admit  that  an  empirical  fact  or  sensuous  datum  may 
be  a  valid  beginning  for  any  genuinely  philosophical  in 
vestigation.  It  is  true,  of  course,  that  Hegel  stands  in  the 
history  of  thought  for  his  insistence  on  the  inseparability 
irTr.  by  Speirs  and  Sanderson,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  327. 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA  33 

of  thought  and  reality,  and  thought  and  experience,  but  it 
seems  as  if  in  passages  like  this  his  practice  falls  short  of  his 
best  theory. 

Now  Spinoza  himself,  while  always  keeping  in  the  back  of 
his  mind  his  ideal  of  a  perfect,  logical  deduction,  recognized 
its  impracticability  for  particular  matters  of  study  In  his 
treatise  On  the  Improvement  of  the  Understanding,  for  example, 
he  describes  the  progress  of  science  in  a  surprisingly  modern 
spirit.  Learning  the  truth,  he  says,  is  like  making  tools.  We 
make  simple  tools  first  and  accomplish  with  them  simple 
feats;  gradually  we  make  more  complex  tools,  until  finally 
we  make  complicated  mechanisms.  "So,  in  like  manner, 
the  intellect,  by  its  native  strength,  makes  for  itself  intellec 
tual  instruments,  whereby  it  acquires  strength  for  performing 
other  intellectual  operations,  and  from  these  operations  gets 
again  fresh  instruments,  or  the  power  of  pushing  its  investiga 
tions  further,  and  thus  gradually  proceeds  till  it  reaches  the 
summit  of  wisdom."  l  Of  course,  Spinoza  believed  that, 
ideally,  all  reasoning  should  flow  from  the  adequate  concep 
tion  of  God,  but  he  admits  that  this  "never,  or  rarely,  hap 
pens,"  2  and  failing  this  ideal  beginning,  his  instructions  were 
to  begin  anywhere  and  achieve  whatever  was  possible.  It  is 
conceivable,  to  be  sure,  that  Spinoza  might  have  recognized 
theoretically  the  necessity  of  limitation  in  intellectual  en 
deavor  and  the  importance  of  reference  to  experience,  and 
yet  in  practice  have  left  the  determination  of  particular 
problems  to  rationalistic  preconceptions.  It  was  Hegel's 
opinion,  we  have  noticed,  that  Spinoza's  treatment  of  the 
moral  life  exhibits  a  sharp  change  in  method,  that  he  turns 
from  rationalism  to  empiricism.  This,  I  believe,  is  true  if 
empiricism  is  broadly  interpreted.  We  find  Spinoza  himself 
contrasting  his  method  in  Part  I  of  the  Ethics  with  his 
method  in  Part  V.  "Although  in  Part  1,1  showed  in  general 
terms,"  he  says,  "that  all  things  .  .  .  depend  .  .  .  on  God, 
yet  that  demonstration  .  .  .  does  not  affect  our  mind  so 
much,  as  when  the  same  conclusion  is  derived  from  the  actual 
essence  of  some  particular  thing."  The  superiority  lies  in  the 
lPp.  i if.  *  Ibid.,  p.  16. 


34  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

fact,  he  says,  that  now  "the  manner  and  way"  become  clear 
to  us.1 

The  true  test  of  the  validity  of  Hegel's  interpretation 
appears  at  this  point.  Granting  to  Hegel  that  the  content 
and  starting-point  of  Spinoza's  treatment  of  the  moral  life 
are  taken  from  experience,  does  Hegel's  conclusion  follow, 
namely,  that  Spinoza's  ethical  system  is  applicable  only  to  a 
world  of  appearance  and  possesses  little  or  no  philosophical 
significance?  Or  is  it  possible  that  Spinoza,  in  leading  us,  as 
it  were,  by  the  hand,  from  a  consideration  of  particular 
things  to  a  knowledge  of  our  highest  blessedness,  so  trans 
forms  his  conception  of  substance  and  mode  that  at  least 
a  degree  of  organic  interdependence  is  exhibited?  If  he  did 
this,  he  not  only  transcended  the  abstractness  of  his  own 
earlier  point  of  view,  a  possibility  which  does  not  seem  to 
have  occurred  to  Hegel,  but  he  did  it  by  employing  a  method 
which  Hegel  considered  fatal,  by  starting  with  man's  expe 
rience  instead  of  with  God. 

Spinoza's  more  abstract  view  of  the  relation  of  things  to 
substance  is  that  of  a  falling  away,  diminution,  or  emanation. 
God  is  necessary  to  things,  but  things  are  not  necessary  to 
God.  It  is  difficult  to  see  how  they  could  stand  otherwise  to 
each  other  when  the  logical  ideal  is  deduction.  If  true 
thought  is  bound  to  proceed  by  drawing  particulars  out  of 
an  original  universal  conception,  the  dependence  must  be 
one-sided.  But  when  in  Part  V  Spinoza  comes  to  the  anal 
ysis  of  man's  power  and  virtue,  he  seems  to  become  impressed 
with  the  truth  that  "the  more  we  understand  particular 
things,  the  more  do  we  understand  God."  2  Everything  in 
the  world,  inanimate  nature  as  well  as  animate,  the  actions 
of  the  wicked  as  well  as  those  of  the  good,  come  from  God 
and  depend  on  Him  in  some  sense,  but  they  are  not  equally 
close  to  or  representative  of  Him.  This  insistence  on  degrees 
in  reality  and  distinction  between  a  greater  and  less  capacity 
to  express  God's  nature  is  an  essential  aspect  of  a  concrete 
view  of  the  relation  of  things  to  God.  On  the  basis  of  such 

1  Ethics,  Pt.  V,  Prop,  xxxvi,  note;  pp.  265 f. 

2  Ibid.,  Pt.  V,  Prop,  xxiv;  p.  260. 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA  35 

a  distinction  Spinoza  says  that  dependence  on  God  may 
best  be  understood  "by  considering,  not  stocks  and  plants, 
but  the  most  reasonable  and  perfect  creatures."  l  "A  mouse 
no  less  than  an  angel,  and  sorrow  no  less  than  joy  depend  on 
God,"  but  the  angel  and  joy  are  better  indices  of  God's 
character.2  If  we  ask  what  is  most  God-like  in  this  world, 
Spinoza  would  answer:  God  is  clear  thinking,  free  activity, 
and  joyful  emotion.  He  is  these  things,  for  "Our  mind  in  so 
far  as  it  knows  itself  and  the  body  under  the  form  of  eternity, 
has  to  that  extent  a  knowledge  of  God."  3  When  Professor 
Pringle-Pattison  is  criticising  Mr.  Bradley's  theory  of  the 
Absolute,  he  identifies  that  phase  of  the  metaphysics  in  which 
individuality  is  lost  in  the  Absolute  as  Spinozistic,  and  that 
phase  which  insists  upon  degrees  in  reality  as  Hegelian.  To 
call  the  loss  of  all  individuality  in  substance  the  sum  of 
Spinozism  is  to  adopt  the  Hegelian  interpretation  as  a  whole, 
to  say  that  things  are  dropped  into  'an  abyss  of  annihila 
tion,'  and  to  neglect  what  we  may  call  this  Hegelian  aspect 
of  Spinozism. 

The  objection  may  be  raised  at  this  point  that  Spinoza  and 
Hegel  meant  different  things  by  degrees  of  reality,  that  for 
Spinoza  the  conception  signified  nothing  more  than  quantity 
of  abstract  being.  If  this  were  true,  Hegel's  objection  would 
hold:  "Mind  to  be  sure  is  more  than  Nature  and  the  animal 
is  more  than  the  plant:  but  we  know  very  little  of  these 
objects  and  the  distinction  between  them,  if  a  more  and  less 
is  enough  for  us."  4  But  by  saying  that  mind  in  its  eternity 
is  God,  Spinoza  meant  that  God  is  of  that  distinctive  quality 
or  kind  that  clear  thinking  is.  Spinoza's  statement  that  he 
will  undertake  to  examine  only  those  particular  determina 
tions  of  God  which  will  help  us  to  understand  ourselves  and 
our  highest  happiness,5  prepares  us  for  the  revelation  of  an 
ideal  experience  which  shall  include  clear  thinking,  free 
activity,  and  joyful  emotion.  We  are  to  be  led  from  the 
notion  of  things  to  the  notion  of  perfection.  This  is,  I  think, 

1  Correspondence,  p.  342.  3  Ethics,  Pt.  V,  Prop,  xxx;  p.  262. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  348.  4  Logic,  tr.  by  Wallace,  p.  188. 

5  Ethics,  Pt.  II,  Preface;  p.  82. 


36  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

quite  in  the  spirit  of  some  remarks  of  Professor  Bosanquet, 
whose  view  of  reality  is  unquestionably  concrete;  for  exam 
ple:  "The  general  direction  of  our  higher  experience  is  a  clue 
to  the  direction  in  which  perfection  has  to  be  sought."  1  It 
is  not  strange  that  in  this  perfection  or  ideality  the  missing 
community  of  significance  between  God  and  His  manifesta 
tions  is  found.  But  if  it  be  found,  we  are  far  removed  from 
the  abstract  ontology  of  the  doctrine  of  substance,  and 
Hegel's  interpretation  is  only  half  true;  for  with  mutual  im 
plications  and  identity  of  meaning  between  the  universal 
and  the  particular  the  notion  of  their  absolute  separation  is 
abandoned,  and  there  is  movement  toward  an  organic  view 
of  the  universe. 

To  develop  this  concrete  phase  of  Spinozism  it  ought  to 
be  possible  to  define  more  or  less  in  detail  the  ideal  experience 
in  which  man  and  God  meet.  A  complete  demonstration  of 
the  manner  in  which  man  realizes  God's  nature  and  power 
cannot  be  required,  for  that  would  presuppose  omniscience 
in  the  demonstrator;  but  the  outlines  of  the  method  should 
be  plain. 

The  organizing  principle  of  the  moral  life,  then,  is  reason  or 
clear  thinking.  Good  conduct  is  action  in  the  light  of  ad 
equate  ideas.  Exactly  what  does  Spinoza  understand  ^the 
function^oLhuman^ reason  to  be?  We  have  already  seen  that, 
ideally,  reason  traces  a  necessary  connection  of  essences 
from  a  logical  prius.  Spinoza  got  this  ideal  from  philosoph 
ical  rationalism  and  from  mathematics,  not  from  observa 
tion  of  the  ordinary  organization  of  experience.  But  when 
Spinoza  is  confronted  by  a  specific  problem,  his  theory  of 
the  understanding  undergoes  a  process  of  definition  or  concre 
tion.  It  then  becomes  apparent  that  Spinoza's  fundamental 
concern  was  not  after  all  so  much  for  the  tracing  of  nec 
essary  connection  in  the  form  of  deduction  as  for  the  realiza 
tion  of  the  necessity  of  the  connection.  What  the  Spinozistic 
reason  cannot  admit  is  the  taking  refuge  in  "the  sanctuary 
of  ignorance";  reality  is  intelligible  through  and  through. 
It  is  not  cause  in  general  but  relevant  cause  in  which  Spinoza 
1  The  Principle  of  Individuality  and  Value,  p.  19. 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA  37 

is  finally  interested,  explanation  how  an  event  came  nec 
essarily  from  a  particular  situation.  For  example,  the  rem 
edy  which  he  suggests  for  excessive  appetites  and  desires 
is  not  a  stiffening  of  the  will  but  the  perception  of  the 
conditions  which  give  rise  to  the  undesirable  passion,  the 
substitution  of  a  complete  analysis  of  the  situation  for 
a  vague  idea.  An  immoderate  love  of  money  or  an  over- 
concern  with  the  arts  of  gain  cannot  be  transformed  into 
a  saner  emotion  by  the  acquisition  of  the  desired  wealth, 
but  rather  by  reflection  upon  the  true  sources  of  content 
ment,  the  true  uses  of  money,  and  the  measure  of  wealth 
which  is  necessary  for  our  actual  needs.1  When  a  man 
realizes  that  the  happiness  which  he  has  lacked  is  to  a  large 
extent  within  his  own  power,  the  true  knowledge  fills  his 
spirit  with  joy.  Wrath  at  an  insult  may  be  best  overcome 
by  reflecting  on  the  ways  in  which  human  nature  responds 
to  different  types  of  treatment.  An  imperfect  theory  would 
prescribe  the  return  of  insult  for  insult,  but  adequate  think 
ing  shows  that  the  analogy  of  physical  conquest  does  not 
hold  in  the  world  of  free  spiritual  activity.  "He  who  chooses 
to  avenge  wrongs  with  hatred  is  assuredly  wretched.  But 
he  who  strives  to  conquer  hatred  with  love  fights  his  battle 
in  joy  and  confidence;  he  withstands  many  as  easily  as  one, 
and  has  very  little  need  of  fortune's  aid.  Those  whom  he 
vanquishes  yield  joyfully,  not  through  failure,  but  through 
increase  in  their  powers."  2  "Minds  are  not  conquered  by 
force,  but  by  love  and  high-mindedness."  3  Similarly  lust 
and  false  ambition  may  be  corrected.  The  seeker  after 
virtue  is  to  frame  a  system  of  right  conduct  for  himself  by 
imagining  the  particular  temptations  and  dangers  to  which 
he  is  liable  and  by  thinking  carefully  how  they  may  best  be 
met.  These  are  illustrations  of  the  fact  that  when  Spinoza 
deals  with  a  specific  problem  he  conceives  of  the  intellect  as 
an  organ  of  specific  response  and  of  the  necessary  order  and 
connection  of  ideas  as  a  concrete  coherence  determined  by 

1  Ethics,  Pt.  IV,  Appendix,  xxix;  p.  242. 

2  Ibid.,  Pt.  IV,  Prop.  XLVI;  p.  220. 

3  Ibid.,  Pt.  IV,  Appendix,  xi;  p.  238. 


38  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

individual  needs.  Now  the  more  a  man  grows  toward  per 
fection,  the  more  extensive  and  pertinent  his  body  of  knowl 
edge  becomes;  as  Spinoza  would  put  it,  the  more  he  is  able 
to  refer  ideas  and  bodily  modifications  to  the  idea  of  God. 
If,  on  the  basis  of  the  doctrine  of  degrees  of  reality,  we  carry 
this  conception  of  concrete  logical  connection  to  its  limit, 
we  reach  the  conception  of  God  as  the  absolute  coherence 
of  thoughts  and  things.  That  is  to  say,  the  early  dogma 
that  "the  order  and  connection  of  ideas  is  the  same  as  the 
order  and  connection  of  things"  is  converted  through  the 
agency  of  specific  problems  into  an  at  least  partially  grasped 
notion  of  a  concrete  universal.  Spinoza  is  half  conscious 
of  his  method  and  half  unconscious,  but  he  comes  nearer  to 
Hegel's  own  organic  view  than  Hegel  ever  admits. 

The  conative  aspect  of  the  ideal  experience  is  called  by 
Spinoza  action  as  distinguished  from  passion  and  freedom 
as  distinguished  from  slavery,  and  here  the  life  of  man  and 
the  life  of  God  again  meet.  At  first  it  is  possible  to  observe 
only  a  general  identity  of  meaning  in  the  fact  that  "God 
acts  solely  by  the  laws  of  his  own  nature,  and  is  not  con 
strained  by  anyone,"  1  and  that  the  free  man  is,  of  all  par 
ticular  things,  least  determined  to  action  by  outside  forces 
and  most  perfectly  explained,  as  to  his  conduct,  by  his  own 
nature.  That  is,  Spinoza  rejected  the  definition  of  freedom  * 
as  indetermination.  As  substance  is  that  the  very  concep 
tion  of  which  excludes  the  conception  of  any  other  being  to 
limit  it,  so  a  free  man  is  his  own  master  and  does  not  lie  at 
the  mercy  of  fortune. 

But  the  similarity  lies  deeper.    So  long  as  it  is  found  only 
in  the  lack  of  coercion  from  without  and  not  in  the  char 
acter  of  the  agents  themselves,  doubt  is  cast  upon  the  very 
existence  of  the  similarity,  for  how  can  the  action  of  an 
insignificant  creature  be  compared  with  the  action  issuing 
from  the  omnipotence  of  God?     The  contention  must  be 
supported,  then,  by  a  demonstration  of  the  degrees  of  reality      . 
as  manifested  in  active  selves.    In  a  word,  free  action  is  self-   ' 
determination.     But   how   comprehensive   a   thing   may   a 
1  Ethics,  Pt.  I,  Prop,  xvn;  p.  59. 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA  39 

self  be,  and  does  it  include  a  principle  of  development?  The 
self  is  conceived  by  Spinoza  not  as  a  fixed  and  limited  point, 
but  as  a  principle  involving  definite  relationships.  In  the 
first  place,  it  is  a  social  principle,  binding  man  to  his  fellows. 
Free  men  are  thoroughly  grateful  to  each  other  through  their 
identity  of  aim.  If  an  act  is  willed  by  a  consciousness  in 
which  this  sense  of  social  solidarity  is  highly  developed,  it 
proceeds  as  it  were  from  a  more  comprehensive  unity  than 
the  act  of  a  man  who  holds  himself  in  opposition  to  his 
fellows.  But  this  principle  is  ultimately  more  than  social;  it 
is  religious.  It  leads  the  expanding  human  consciousness 
through  the  feeling  of  union  with  his  fellow-men  to  a  feeling 
of  his  union  with  nature  and  God.  "The  endeavor  of  the 
better  part  of  ourselves  is  in  harmony  with  the  order  of  nature 
as  a  whole."  1  In  his  treatise  On  the  Improvement  of  the 
Understanding  Spinoza  describes  his  ideal  as  follows:  "As  it 
is  a  part  of  my  happiness  to  lend  a  helping  hand  that  many 
others  may  understand  even  as  I  do,"  so  it  is  my  chief  good 
to  "arrive,  with  other  individuals  if  possible,  at  the  knowl 
edge  of  the  union  existing  between  the  mind  and  the  whole 
of  nature."  2  Our  conclusion  is  that  the  greater  the  freedom 
or  power  of  activity  pertaining  to  the  self,  the  more  com 
prehensive  the  individuality  to  which  it  pertains.  If  this  be 
true,  God,  as  the  absolutely  free,  is  the  absolutely  individual. 
Compare  this  interpretation  with  Professor  Bosanquet's,  for 
example;  he  says,  "When  freedom  and  spontaneity  reach 
their  climax  in  religion,  the  self  no  longer  insists  on  its 
exclusive  claim,  and  the  whole  being  goes  out  together  into 
the  service  which  is  perfect j; freedom,"  and,  "It  is  plain  that 
the  height  of  individualitjGs  to  be  looked  for  in  experiences 
which  raise  to  the  acutest  pitch  the  sense  and  fact  of  identity 
with  man  nature  and  God."  3 

Besides  reason  and  freedom,  there  is  the  emotion  of  pleas 
ure  as  a  third  thread  of  connection  between  human  moral     * 
striving  and  the  perfection  of  God's  nature.    It  is  one  proof 
of  the  dependence  of  Spinoza's  theory  on  empirical  observa 
tion  that  he  recognizes  the  fact  that  the  stimulus  of  feeling 

1  Ethics,  Pt.  IV,  Appendix,  xxxn;  p.  243.     2  P.  6.     3  Op.  cit.,  p.  271. 


40  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

is  necessary  to  provoke  action.  Rationalist  though  he  is, 
right  reason,  in  the  absence  of  the  warmth  of  emotion,  cannot 
guarantee  virtuous  conduct.1  But  surely  pleasure,  taken 
abstractly,  may  incite  to  any  kind  of  conduct,  and  may  ac 
company  conduct  remote  from  divine.  The  question  arises 
for  the  third  time:  Did  Spinoza  recognize  degrees  of  worth? 
There  are  in  his  theory  two  kinds  of  pleasure,  the  passion, 
which  may  be  excessive  or  localized  or  dependent  for  its 
continuance  on  the  continuance  of  an  external  stimulation, 
and  which  may  quickly  change  into  dejection;  and  the  active 
emotion,  which  is  simple  and  abiding  and  is  the  result  of  an 
enlarging  vision  and  an  expanding  personality.  We  have 
seen  that  an  individual  may  grow  until  he  approaches  God 
by  means  of  the  assertion  of  more  and  more  necessary  connec 
tions  between  things,  and  that  finally  he  comprehends  in  his 
own  understanding,  as  nearly  as  may  be,  the  universal 
coherence  of  nature.  There  is  no  substitute  for  Spinoza's 
own  description  of  the  increasing  joy  that  accompanies  this 
growth  in  understanding.  "The  power  which  clear  and  dis 
tinct  knowledge  .  .  .  possesses  .  .  .  causes  the  passions  to 
occupy  a  very  small  part  of  the  mind.  .  .  .  Further,  it 
begets  a  love  toward  a  thing  immutable  and  eternal,  whereof 
we  may  really  enter  into  possession;  neither  can  it  be  defiled 
with  those  faults  which  are  inherent  in  ordinary  love;  but 
it  may  grow  from  strength  to  strength,  and  may  engross  the 
greater  part  of  the  mind,  and  deeply  penetrate  it."  2  On  the 
whole  Spinoza  is  here  again  forced  away  from  his  doctrine 
of  an  indeterminate  substance,  for  he  perceives  that  man, 
when  affected  by  the  highest  type  of  emotion,  is  experiencing 
a  divine  experience.  Just  as  the  love  of  God  is  the  crowning 
form  of  the  emotional  life  for  man,  so  God's  love  of  himself 
is  God's  pleasure.  "The  intellectual  love  of  the  mind  to 
wards  God  is  that  very  love  of  God  whereby  God  loves  him 
self."  3  It  is  in  harmony  with  Hegel's  own  more  concrete 

1  Ethics,  Pt.  IV,  Prop,  xiv;  p.  198. 

2  Ibid.,  Pt.  V,  Prop,  xx,  note;  p.  258. 

3  Ibid.,  Pt.  V,  Prop,  xxxvi;  p.  264.    Even  Hegel  admits  that  at  this  one 
point  there  is  some  sort  of  logical  connection  between  Spinoza's  system 


HEGEL'S  CRITICISM  OF  SPINOZA  41 

view  of  reality  to  say  that  God  may  be  expressed  in  the 
essence  of  the  human  mind  and  that  human  understanding 
and  freedom  and  joy  are  God's  nature  shining  through  par 
ticularity. 

A  sense  of  oneness  with  God  is  for  Spinoza  the  spring  of 
virtue  in  humanity.  The  source  of  virtue  and  virtue  can  no 
more  be  separated  in  Spinoza's  theory  than  the  reward  of 
virtue  and  virtue.  The  realization  of  the  unity  which  exists 
between  man  and  the  whole  of  nature  is  the  positive  and 
moving  principle  to  righteousness,  and  blessedness  is  the 
sense  of  having  acted  in  accordance  with  that  principle.1 
Spinoza  evidently  neither  separated  motive  and  endeavor 
nor  endeavor  and  fruition;  they  are  all  united  in  the  ideal 
experience. 

These  are  some  indications  of  the  concrete  aspect  of 
Spinoza's  thought,  and  they  are,  it  seems  to  me,  a  sufficient 
refutation  of  the  strict  Hegelian  view  that,  according  to 
Spinoza,  God  forever  remains  separate  from  His  world  and 
never  pervades  it,  and  that  the  moral  struggle  of  man  is  a 
mere  phenomenon  in  the  abstract  world  of  appearance. 

of  ethics  and  his  principle  of  absolute  substance;  Philosophy  of  Religion, 
tr.  by  Speirs  and  Sanderson,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  327. 
1  Ethics  j  Pt.  V,  Prop.  XLII;  p.  270. 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY 
GEORGE  HOLLAND  SABINE 

THE  writing  of  the  history  of  philosophy  falls  inevitably 
into  certain  conventional  interpretations  which  serve  the 
purposes  of  rough  classification  but  which,  for  that  very 
reason,  frequently  lead  to  formalism.  Such  classifications 
can  never  do  more  than  schematize  a  few  of  the  actual  his 
torical  relations  of  systems  and  they  easily  become  mis- 
representative  by  what  they  leave  out .  and  one-sided  by 
what  they  include.  A  case  in  point  is  the  usual  interpretation 
of  the  philosophy  which  is  universally  described  as  English 
empiricism.  Nobody  can  doubt  that  English  philosophy 
from  Locke  to  Hume  represents  the  evolution  of  a  certain 
point  of  view.  But  it  is  at  best  a  doubtful  terminology  to 
pre-empt  so  broad  a  word  as  empiricism  for  this  single  period 
and  it  is  positively  misleading  to  represent  the  period  as  a 
self-contained  process  in  which  empiricism  pure  and  simple 
came  to  its  final  expression. 

It  is  indeed  common  to  recognize  that  the  immediate 
stimulus  to  Locke's  philosophy  was  the  Cartesian  rationalism 
and  that  at  most  Locke  was  an  empiricist  only  so  far  as  his 
theory  of  the  origin  of  ideas  is  concerned;  his  account  of 
knowledge  in  the  Fourth  Book  of  the  Essay  is  quite  man 
ifestly  rationalist.  This  rationalism,  however,  is  usually 
regarded  as  a  foreign  element  in  Locke  which  it  was  the 
problem  of  the  later  empiricists  to  remove.  It  is  indeed 
a  fact  that  Berkeley  and  Hume  were  largely  engaged  in 
following  the  lead  given  by  Locke's  Second  Book.  Berkeley's 
analysis  of  the  visual  perception  of  depth,  his  reduction  of- 
material  substance  to  sensations,  and  his  explanation  of  the 
physical  order  as  a  coherence  of  sensations  may  all  be  re 
garded  in  this  light,  as  may  also  Hume's  analysis  of  nec 
essary  connection  in  cause  and  effect  and  his  reduction  of 


t 
RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  43 

the  self  to  a  bundle  of  sensations.  ,A11  these  investigations 
were  certainly,  on  one  side  at  least,  a  search  for  the  impres 
sions  from  which  ideas  originate.  In  addition,  however,  it 
has  commonly  been  inferred  that  the  extension  of  this  search 
over  a  broader  and  broader  field  meant  that  empiricism  was 
gaining  a  more  and  more  consistent  expression.  Hence  it  is 
often  said  that  the  logic  of  English  empiricism  completes 
itself  in  scepticism.  "It  is  in  virtue  of  the  relentless  faith 
fulness  with  which  he  [Hume]  follows  out  the  consequences 
of  the  empirical  point  of  view  that  we  are  compelled  to  admit 
that  in  the  Treatise  of  Human  Nature  the  logic  of  empiricism 
works  itself  out  to  its  inevitable  conclusions.  ...  He  is  an 
empiricist  pure  and  simple,  and  he  shows  us  with  singular 
insight  the  ultimate  meaning  and  consequences  of  pure 
empiricism."  l 

It  by  no  means  follows,  however,  that  the  extension  of 
empiricism  meant  the  extrusion  of  rationalism,  or  that  this 
element  of  Locke's  thought  was  successfully  sloughed  off 
by  Hume.  It  is  indeed  true  that  Locke's  rationalism  failed 
to  develop,  and  it  is  part  of  the  purpose  of  this  paper  to 
show  that  this  part  of  his  philosophy  was  so  devitalized,  so 
false  to  the  insight  of  rationalism  as  a  living  method  in  the 
hands  of  Descartes,  that  it  was  not  capable  of  developing. 
But  Locke's  rationalism  did  not  disappear,  and  it  will  be 
shown  further  that  it  remained  as  firmly  imbedded  in  the 
philosophy  of  Hume  as  ever  it  had  been  in  that  of  Locke. 
Hence  it  is  seriously  misleading  to  say  that  Hume  was  an 
empiricist  "pure  and  simple";  such  a  view  arises  by  neglect 
ing  the  more  or  less  tacit  assumptions  that  lie  in  the  back 
ground  of  Hume's  philosophy  but  none  the  less  effectively 
determine  the  nature  of  his  conclusions.  So  far  as  his  ideal 
of  what  ought  to  constitute  true  knowledge  is  concerned, 
Hume  is  almost  if  not  quite  as  much  a  rationalist  as  Locke; 

1  J.  Seth,  English  Philosophers  and  Schools  of  Philosophy,  p.  150.    The 
quotation  is  given  merely  as  an  illustration  of  the  usual  interpretation 
of  Hume;  Professor  Seth  goes  farther  than  many  critics  in  recognizing  ' 
the  effects  of  rationalism  upon  the  English  philosophy  of  the  eighteenth 
century. 


44  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

his  extension  of  empirical  principles  consists  largely  in 
irrefutable  proofs  that  the  rationalist  ideal  is  unattainable, 
a  suspicion  which  Locke  shared,  though  with  only  the  most 
confused  perception  of  its  consequences.  From  this  con 
junction  of  ideals  and  results  Hume's  scepticism  inevitably 
follows.  His  ideal  of  science  is  a  system  of  judgments  de 
ductively  related,  while  the  materials  of  knowledge  are 
sensations.  Between  sensations  deductive  relations  are  not 
discoverable,  and  the  materials  with  which  we  work  are 
therefore  quite  incapable  of  giving  the  results  which  the 
ideal  demands.  The  point  of  view  which  we  find  developing 
from  Locke  to  Hume  is  therefore  not  empiricism  pure  and 
simple,  but  empiricism  on  a  persistent  background  of  ill- 
conceived  rationalism.  Hume's  scepticism  is  not  the  in 
evitable  result  of  empiricism;  it  is  the  consequence  of  devel- 
oping  an  empirical  method  and  judging  the  outcome  by  a 
rationalist  standard.1 

In  order  to  appreciate  properly  the  influence  of  the  ra 
tionalist  ideal  of  science  upon  English  philosophers,  it  will 
be  necessary  to  observe  briefly  the  source  from  which  that 
ideal  was  derived.  No  other  special  science  has  ever  dom 
inated  theory  of  knowledge  to  anything  like  the  same  extent 
as  mathematics  during  the  seventeenth  and  eighteenth 
centuries.  The  unquestionable  certainty  of  mathematical 
knowledge  was  universally  recognized,  not  less  by  those  who 
were  called  empiricists  than  by  the  rationalists.  It  appeared 
as  obvious  to  Locke  as  to  Descartes  or  Spinoza;  the  accept 
ance  of  mathematics  as  the  very  type  of  scientific  certainty 
is  indeed  a  common  characteristic  of  the  period,  shared  by 
philosophies  otherwise  the  most  diverse.  With  this  exalta 
tion  of  mathematics  came,  moreover,  the  conviction  that 
the  method  of  mathematics  is  the  key  to  certainty  in  all 
sciences.  This  belief  in  a  single,  all-inclusive  method  was 
another  common  characteristic  of  the  period.  The  mediaeval 
lesson  of  universalism  had  not  as  yet  been  unlearned.  It 
was  not  more  obvious  to  the  theologian  that  there  must  be 
one  and  only  one  true  church  than  it  was  to  the  philosopher 
1  Cf.  Windelband,  Gesch.  d.  n.  Ph.,  Vol.  I,  p.  346. 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  45 

that  human  knowledge  must  be  all  of  one  piece,  developed 
throughout  by  the  application  to  all  subject-matters  of  a 
single  intellectual  activity.  The  failure  of  mediaeval  philos 
ophy  to  create  such  a  system,  and  the  inadequacy  of  the 
Aristotelian  logic  to  carry  such  a  burden,  were  indeed  man 
ifest,  but  the  ideal  persisted  and  the  hopes  of  the  moderns 
centered  for  the  time  being  in  the  method  of  mathematics. 
The  classical  expression  of  this  ideal  and  the  first  systematic 
effort  to  carry  it  through  is  the  rationalism  of  Descartes. 
In  his  early  Rules  for  the  Direction  of  the  Mind,1  he  presents 
philosophy  as  a  universal  mathematics,  a  general  study  of 
order  and  measurement  by  a  method  which  alone  can  im 
prove  the  "natural  light  of  reason"  and  thus  do  away  with 
that  patchwork  of  tradition,  prejudice,  and  unfounded  sur 
mise  which  he  regarded  as  the  scandal  of  the  accepted  learn 
ing.  How  persistently  he  clung  to  this  ideal  of  a  universal 
method  may  be  seen  in  the  later  Discourse  and  indeed  in 
almost  any  of  his  writings  upon  philosophy. 

A  unanimity  so  general  as  this  acceptance  of  the  math 
ematical  ideal  can  be  explained  only  by  a  deep-lying  cause, 
and  this  cause  is  to  be  found  in  the  pre-eminent  importance 
of  mathematics  in  the  method  of  the  new  natural  science. 
This  method  involved,  indeed,  the  systematic  use  of  observa 
tion  and  may  therefore  be  called  in  a  general  sense  empirical, 
but  its  novelty  depended  in  a  far  more  profound  sense  upon 
the  guiding  of  induction  by  the  ideal  of  a  mathematical 
formulation  of  results.  The  induction  is  directed  essentially 
to  the  exact  measurement  of  phenomena  and  to  the  discovery 
of  constant  numerical  relations.  This  is  the  new  form  which 
modern  science  gave  to  the  ancient  ideal  of  simplicity  and 
harmony  in  nature.  The  combination  of  deduction  and 
induction  is  the  new  logical  discovery  of  the  physical  sciences. 
Only  mathematics  offers  a  sound  means  of  deduction;  only 
measurement  offers  the  means  of  really  objective  observation. 
"What  shall  we  say,  Simplicio?"  says  Sagredo  in  Galileo's 
Dialogues  concerning  Two  New  Sciences.2  "Must  we  not  con- 

1  Written  in  1628  but  not  printed  until  1701. 
2Tr.  by  Crew  and  de  Salvio,  p.  137. 


46  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

fess  that  geometry  is  the  most  powerful  of  all  instruments 
for  sharpening  the  wit  and  training  the  mind  to  think  cor 
rectly?  Was  not  Plato  perfectly  right  when  he  wished  that 
his  pupils  should  be  first  of  all  well  grounded  in  mathemat 
ics  ? "  And  Simplicio  answers,  "  Indeed  I  begin  to  understand 
that  while  logic  is  an  excellent  guide  in  discourse,  it  does  not, 
as  regards  stimulation  to  discovery,  compare  with  the  power 
of  sharp  distinction  which  belongs  to  geometry."  Again, 
observation  guided  by  the  assumption  that  nature  must 
show  simple  mathematical  relations  is  recognized  by  Galileo 
as  the  essential  novelty  of  his  own  method  when  he  points 
out,  in  the  opening  sentences  of  his  discourse  De  motu  locali, 
that  he  has  created  a  new  science  dealing  with  a  very  old 
subject  by  bringing  to  light  such  facts  as  that  the  distances 
traversed  by  a  freely  falling  body  in  successive  units  of  time 
are  in  the  ratios  1:3:5,  etc.,  or  that  the  path  of  a  projectile 
is  a  parabola.1  The  triumph  of  Galileo's  science  lies  in  his 
conception  of  uniformly  accelerated  motion,  a  conception 
which  led  eventually  to  the  clarification  of  the  conceptions 
of  mass  and  force,  in  a  word,  to  nothing  less  than  modern 
dynamics.2  He  described  accurately  the  point  of  view  of 
physical  science  when  he  said  that  the  only  qualities  which 
we  are  obliged  to  attribute  to  things  are  figure,  magnitude, 
and  motion.  The  rationalism  of  Descartes  derived  its 
vitality  from  the  fact  that  it  was  at  bottom  a  generalization 
of  the  ideals  which  actually  guided  the  scientific  study  of 
moving  bodies.  When  he  makes  extension  the  essence  of 
matter,  he  is  merely  saying  what  Kepler  had  said  more 
picturesquely  in  his  famous  dictum,  Ubi  materia,  ibi  geo- 
metria.  Rationalism  was  in  a  special  sense  the  philosophy  of 
exact  natural  science;  it  stood  for  the  scientific  achievement 
of  the  period  in  a  way  that  English  empiricism  never  did. 

Thus  we  find  at  once  the  cause  for  the  overshadowing  in 
fluence  of  mathematics  and  the  reasons  which  determined 
the  form  of  Descartes'  theory  of  knowledge.  This  theory 
turns  upon  his  belief  in  clear  and  distinct  ideas.  The  attain- 

1  Two  New  Sciences,  tr.  by  Crew  and  de  Salvio,  p.  153. 

2  E.  Mach,  Science  of  Mechanics,  tr.  by  McCormack,  pp.  I28ff. 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  47 

ment  of  knowledge  depends  upon  observing  the  rule  that 
nothing  is  to  be  asserted  which  is  capable  of  being  doubted. 
The  first  step,  accordingly,  must  be  the  discovery  of  the 
simplest  intuitive  truths, — the  simple  aspects  of  things  and 
the  simple  logical  relations  between  them, — which  by  their 
inherent  clearness  and  distinctness  carry  the  guarantee  of 
their  certainty  with  them.  Knowledge  must  begin  with 
innate  ideas  or  simple  natures.  This  search  for  the  simple_ 
is  the  secret  of  scientific  success,  as  the  vulgar  tendency  to 
depreciate  the  simple  is  for  Descartes  the  fatal  weakness  of 
earlier  philosophy.  When  knowledge  passes  beyond  the 
simple  natures  it  still  proceeds  by  intuition,  for  deduction 
advances  by  a  series  of  intuitions  which  bring  to  light  the 
necessary  connections  between  simple  natures.  Deduction, 
therefore,  shares  and  extends  the  original  certainty  of  our 
innate  ideas,  for  each  step  is  clear  and  distinct.  Thus  knowl 
edge  advances  triumphantly  from  a  fixed  center,  setting  all 
in  order  as  it  goes,  by  constructing  a  single  deductive  system 
of  concepts.  It  follows  that  knowledge  of  the  senses  can 
never  attain  this  ideal,  for  the  senses  present  us  with  highly 
complicated  matters  of  fact.  We  find,  indeed,  from  our 
experience  that  certain  things  occur  together,  but  we  are 
able  to  perceive  no  necessity  in  their  connections,  and  con 
sequently  we  do  not  scientifically  understand  them  until 
we  have,  by  a  series  of  intuitions,  logically  interrelated  the 
simple  natures  presented.1  In  practice  it  is  the  concept  of 
motion  which  enables  us  to  reduce  the  empirical  variety  of 
the  physical  world.2  An  adequate  knowledge  of  the  laws 
of  motion  would  enable  us  to  foretell  sensuous  qualities  and 
to  understand  their  necessary  connections. 

It  is  abundantly  evident  that  the  theory  of  knowledge 
thus  formulated  by  Descartes  corresponds  in  a  very  real  way 
to  the  most  fruitful  scientific  procedure  of  the  time.  The 
vitality  of  the  mathematical  ideal  is  derived  from  the  close 
ness  of  its  contact  with  the  method  of  exact  physical  science. 
It  is  equally  clear,  however,  that  his  statement  of  the  theory 

1  Cf.  Meditations,  II;  tr.  by  Haldane  and  Ross,  Vol.  I,  pp.  1545. 

2  Cf.  Principles,  II,  23;  ibid.,  p.  265. 


48  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

hovers  always  upon  the  verge  of  falsifying  the  method  which 
gave  it  life.  In  the  hands  of  a  scientific  genius  like  Galileo, 
mathematical  formulation  never  loses  touch  with  experience 
and  induction;  in  the  hands  of  Descartes  the  epistemologist, 
it  too  frequently  suggests  the  evolution  of  experience  from 
the  mere  logical  manipulation  of  concepts.  His  distinction  of 
clear  ideas  and  confused  ones  constantly  tends  to  become 
identified  with  that  between  reason  and  the  senses,  and  as  he 
advances  in  his  theory  of  knowledge  and  his  metaphysics, 
sense  and  reason  become  ever  more  sharply  opposed.  So 
long  as  he  keeps  himself  in  touch  with  actual  scientific  pro 
cedure,  this  tendency  is  held  in  check  by  his  perfectly  clear 
perception  of  the  need  for  experiment  and  of  the  impossibility 
of  using  deduction  as  a  substitute  for  experience.  Consider, 
for  example,  the  following  admirable  statement  of  the  rela 
tion  between  experiment  and  logical  construction:  "In 
subsequently  passing  over  in  my  mind  all  the  objects  which 
have  ever  been  presented  to  my  senses,  I  can  truly  venture 
to  say  that  I  have  not  there  observed  anything  which  I  could 
not  easily  explain  by  the  principles  which  I  had  discovered. 
But  I  must  also  confess  that  the  power  of  nature  is  so  ample 
and  so  vast,  and  these  principles  are  so  simple  and  general, 
that  I  observed  hardly  any  particular  effect  as  to  which  I 
could  not  at  once  recognize  that  it  might  be  deduced  from 
the  principles  in  many  different  ways;  and  my  greatest 
difficulty  is  usually  to  discover  in  which  of  these  ways  the 
effect  does  depend  upon  them.  As  to  that,  I  do  not  know 
any  other  plan  but  again  to  try  to  find  experiments  of  such 
a  nature  that  their  result  is  not  the  same  if  it  has  to  be  ex 
plained  by  one  of  the  methods,  as  it  would  be  if  explained 
by  the  other."  l  Unfortunately,  in  his  theory  of  knowledge 
Descartes  constantly  tends  to  regard  science  as  a  product 
of  pure  thought  which  owes  nothing  essential  to  the  senses. 

The  ideal  of  a  purely  conceptual  science  thus  established 
by  Descartes  is  adopted  without  qualification  by  Locke. 
Between  Locke  and  Descartes,  however,  there  is  this  fun 
damental  difference.    In  Descartes  the  ideal  always  had  been 
1  Method,  Part  VI;  tr.  by  Haldane  and  Ross,  Vol.  I,  p.  121. 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  49 

qualified  by  his  first-hand  knowledge  of  mathematics  and 
its  use  in  scientific  investigation;  in  Locke  it  has  the  stiffness 
and  artificiality  of  an  ideal  taken  at  second-hand  by  a  man 
who  has  no  conception  of  it  as  a  working  method.  Locke 
adopts  entire  Descartes'  theory  of  intuition  and  deduction 
and  regards  mathematics  and  rational  ethics  as  the  only 
subjects  in  which  scientific  certainty  is  possible.  A  science 
of  bodies  is  flatly  declared  to  be  impossible  because  we  cannot 
know  the  'real  essences'  upon  which  the  operations  of  bodies 
depend,1  or  as  Locke  sometimes  says,  because  we  cannot 
know  the  relations  between  the  primary  and  the  secondary 
qualities  of  bodies.  Scientific  explanation  is  thus  naively 
equated  with  the  scholastic  search  for  real  essences,  physico- 
mathematical  analysis  with  the  pursuit  of  a  'cause  of  being.' 
Moreover,  by  an  extension  of  the  Cartesian  dualism  which 
consists  in  taking  it  on  its  least  tenable  side,  Locke  interprets 
Descartes'  simple  natures  and  their  interdependences  as 
ideas  and  the  "connection  and  agreement,  or  disagreement  and 
repugnancy  of  any  of  our  ideas."  The  ideas  of  mathematics 
are  'archetypes  of  the  mind's  own  making'  and  are  certain 
for  precisely  this  reason;  so  far  as  real  existence  is  concerned, 
knowledge  cannot  go  beyond  'probability.'  In  Locke's  in 
terpretation,  Descartes'  deductive  science  becomes  a  mental 
science  and  the  ideal  is  completely  emasculated,  so  far  as  its 
relation  to  the  methods  of  physical  science  is  concerned. 
The  ideal  is  retained,  but  retained  in  such  a  form  that  it 
negates  the  very  science  whose  method  gave  it  vitality. 
With  the  unerring  instinct  of  an  amateur,  Locke  clutches 
all  the  easy  abstractions  in  Descartes'  account  of  his  method 
and  lets  slip  all  the  points  of  contact  with  reality  which  gave 
the  method  life. 

The  rationalism  of  Locke's  Fourth  Book  was  of  a  sort 
which  offered  no  possibilities  of  development;  the  'histor 
ical  plain  method'  of  the  Second  Book,  on  the  other  hand, 
almost  immediately  gave  rise  to  a  brilliant  scientific  dis 
covery.  This  was  Berkeley's  introspective  analysis  of  the 
visual  perception  of  depth  in  his  New  Theory  of  Vision,  1709. 
1  Essay,  Bk.  IV,  Ch.  vi,  §  11;  Frazer's  edition,  Vol.  II,  pp.  26off. 


50  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

This  discovery,  as  the  successors  of  Berkeley  were  not  slow 
to  see,  exhibits  the  true  genius  of  the  method  which  Locke 
had  contributed  to  philosophy.    What  they  did  not  see  was 
that  this  method  is  not  the  empiricism  of  the  exact  physical 
sciences.    The  essence  of  Berkeley's  discovery  lay  in  the  fact 
that  he  showed  an  apparently  simple  visual  perception,—- 
that  of  depth  in  the  third  dimension, — to  be  capable  of 
analysis  into  various  sensational  factors  which  fuse  in  the 
production  of  the  total  perception.    As  Berkeley  never  tires 
of  insisting,  these  sensational  elements  have  no  intuitable 
relation  with  each  other;  there  is  no  agreement  or  disagree 
ment  between  them.    They  merely  fuse  to  form  a  compound 
qualitatively  distinct  from  any  of  them,  and  no  knowledge 
of  the  separate  elements  would  ever  enable  anyone  to  deduce 
the  nature  of  the  compound.    The  fusion  is  exclusively  qual 
itative;   no   possibility  of  measurement   exists   and   math 
ematics  is  of  no  service  whatever  in  the  formulation  of  the 
results.     The  principle  discovered  is  simply  the  statement 
of  an  empirical  correlation,  and  it  rests  primarily  upon  the 
enumeration  of  instances.     It  is  of  course  true  that  such 
empirical  correlations  are  to  be  found  in  the  physical  sciences, 
but  they  are  not  typical  of  mechanics  and  it  is  sheer  confu 
sion  to  equate  enumeration  with  experiment.    On  the  other 
hand,  correlation  by  enumeration  is  thoroughly  typical  of 
psychology,  at  least  in  its  pre-experimental  stage,  and  of 
ethics,  economics,  and  political  science.    English  empiricism 
was  the  empiricism  of  enumeration,  that  is,  of  the  psycholog 
ical  and  social  sciences,  which,  far  more  than  natural  science, 
formed  the  intellectual  environment  in  which  English  philos 
ophy  developed. 

Berkeley's  work  confirmed  the  already  existing  tendency 
to  identify  empirical  method  with  the  counting  of  instances. 
It  remained  to  be  seen  what  effect  this  method  would  have 
upon  the  categories  of  cause  and  substance  and  how  these 
categories,  conceived  as  they  were  in  the  light  of  rationalism, 
would  welcome  the  newcomer.  It  is  at  this  juncture  that 
Hume's  theory  of  knowledge  comes  upon  the  stage. 

Hume's  theory  of  knowledge  requires  to  be  treated  under 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  51 

two  aspects,  his  general  account  of  the  nature  of  knowledge, 
to  which  his  very  unsatisfactory  treatment  of  space  and  time 
is  in  a  general  way  subsidiary,  and  his  analyses  of  bodily 
substance,  cause  and  effect,  and  personal  identity.  The 
first  of  these  aspects  is  commonly  admitted  to  show  the 
remnants  of  Locke's  rationalism  but  it  is  supposed  that  this 
rationalism  was  laid  aside  when  he  went  forward  to  the 
second  aspect,  which  comprises  the  three  great  tasks  of  his 
philosophy.  This  is  not,  however,  a  fact;  rationalism  in  the 
peculiar  form  given  it  by  Locke  remained  to  the  end  an  essen 
tial  factor  in  shaping  Hume's  conclusions. 

In  the  Enquiry  1  Hume  clearly  divides  all  objects  of  knowl- 
edge  into  relations  of  ideas  and  matters  of  fact.  To  the  first 
belong  the  sciences  of  geometry,  algebra,  and  arithmetic; 
their  certainty  is  either  intuitive  or  demonstrative  and  the 
reason  for  this  certainty  is  that  there  is  no  implication  of 
existence  in  this  sort  of  knowledge.  It  deals  only  with  the 
relations  of  ideas.  Matters  of  fact,  on  the  other  hand,  de 
pend  upon  a  different  principle,  for  the  opposite  of  a  matter 
of  fact  is  entirely  conceivable  and  involves  no  contradiction. 
Demonstration  regarding  matters  of  fact  is  impossible;  our 
knowledge  here  rests  upon  cause  and  effect.  In  the  Treatise 
this  distinction  and  the  corresponding  classification  of 
sciences  is  not  used  with  equal  clearness  but  it  is  everywhere 
made.  The  relations,  contradictions,  and  agreements  of 
ideas  are  asserted  to  be  the  foundation  of  all  human  knowl 
edge,  and  demonstration  is  described  as  a  type  of  knowledge 
so  certain  that  it  will  not  even  tolerate  a  difficulty.2  The 
name  knowledge,  strictly  used,  applies  only  to  those  rela 
tions  which  depend  wholly  upon  ideas,  while  all  inferences 
which  involve  real  existence  are  to  be  called  either  proofs 
or  probabilities.3  The  only  substantial  difference  between 
the  Treatise  and  the  Enquiry  is  that  in  the  former  Hume  in 
cludes  geometry  among  sciences  of  observation,  since  it  has 

1  §  IV,  Pt.  I;  Essays,  edited  by  Green  and  Grose,  Vol.  II,  pp.  2off. 

2  Bk.  I,  Pt.  II,  §  2;  pp.  29ff.     The  page  references  throughout  are  to 
Selby-Bigge's  edition  of  the  Treatise. 

3  Bk.  I,  Pt.  Ill,  §  i;  pp.  69rL;  §  11;  p.  124. 


52  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

no  exact  standard  of  equality  or  other  relations  of  quantity; 
algebra  and  arithmetic  alone  are  recognized  as  exact  sciences.1 
It  is  clear,  then,  that  aside  from  removing  the  manifold 
obscurities  and  confusions  in  Locke's  way  of  presenting  the 
matter,  Hume  has  not  altered  the  conclusions  in  any  mate 
rial  respect;  he  is  in  principle  not  a  whit  less  a  rationalist 
than  his  predecessor.  There  is  not  the  slightest  evidence 
that  demonstration  was  for  him  less  the  ideal  of  what  gen 
uine  knowledge  must  be  than  it  had  been  for  Locke.  If  he 
had  little  to  say  about  demonstration,  it  was  doubtless  be 
cause  a  rationalism  conceived  in  Locke's  fashion  left  little 
to  be  said. 

So  far  as  concerns  the  method  of  the  demonstrative 
sciences  Hume  has  no  more  to  say  than  is  given  in  the  passing 
remarks  just  alluded  to.  His  discussion  of  space  and  time, 
which  should  naturally  belong  to  this  part  of  his  system,  is 
difficult  to  make  anything  of,  because  he  crudely  regards 
geometry  as  a  science  of  mere  observation,  though  it  is  not 
concerned  with  matters  of  fact  or  cause  and  effect.  The 
fact  appears  to  be  that  he  had  no  settled  convictions  re 
garding  the  matter,  for  he  does  not  hesitate  to  use  geomet 
rical  theorems  on  occasion  as  examples  of  exact  knowledge, 
in  contrast  with  inferences  based  on  causes.  Unsatisfactory 
as  the  whole  discussion  is,  one  can  easily  see  that  Hume  did 
not  in  fact  apply  the  same  method  to  space  and  time  as  to 
substance  and  causation.  Despite  his  scepticism  regarding 
>-  geometry,  he  could  not  bring  himself  to  regard  space  and 
time  as  fictions  of  the  imagination,  though  his  own  account 
of  them  leads  readily  enough  to  this  conclusion.  His  convic 
tion  that  mathematics,  even  including  geometry,  is  a  real 
science,  was  too  strong  to  permit  him  to  lay  irreverent  hands 
upon  space  and  time.  Had  he  done  so,  the  reductio  ad  ab- 
surdum  of  his  own  rationalism  would  have  been  too  manifest. 
The  essence  of  Hume's  account  of  space  is  his  effort  to 
derive  it  as  a  ' distribution  or  order'  of  colored  and  tangible 
points.  Least  visible  and  least  tangible  impressions  are 
mathematical  points  which  have  a  sort  of  mental  substance 
*  Bk.  I,  Pt.  II,  §  4;  PP.  45ff-;  Pt.  HI,  §  i;  p.  71. 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  53 

because  of  their  visibility  and  tangibility  but  which  are  not 
extended,  because  they  are  simple  impressions  which  could 
not  be  diminished  without  ceasing  to  exist.1  The  possibility 
of  this  curious  notion  is  supported,  be  it  said,  upon  frankly 
a  priori  grounds;  it  could  hardly  have  been  defended  empir 
ically.  Space  is  a  complex  idea  arising  by  the  combination  of 
these  simple  and  unextended  points;  time  is  a  similar  com 
plex  idea  derived  from  the  succession  of  perceptions  of  all 
kinds.  Now  Hume  is  perfectly  explicit  in  his  statement  that 
there  are  no  impressions  of  space  and  time  distinct  from 
sensations  of  vision,  touch,  etc.  These  ideas  arise  only  by 
attending  exclusively  to  the  manner  in  which  colored  and 
tangible  points  are  distributed  or  in  which  impressions  suc 
ceed  one  another.  They  cannot  be  conceived  apart  from 
these  impressions,  though  we  can  attend  to  the  spatial  or 
temporal  distribution  alone.  In  this  case,  therefore,  Hume 
qualifies  his  denial  of  abstract  ideas  in  the  same  fashion  as 
Berkeley.  It  is  clear  that  his  demand  for  an  impression 
corresponding  to  the  ideas  cannot  be  satisfied  any  more  than 
it  can  in  the  case  of  substance  and  cause.  Space  and  time 
are  fictions  of  the  imagination  just  as  much  as  the  concepts 
which  Hume  calls  so.  The  fact  is  concealed  only  because 
he  confuses  an  order  of  points  with  the  mere  addition  of  them. 
We  turn  now  to  the  part  of  Hume's  system  which  made  up 
his  real  contribution  to  philosophy  and  which  has  been  re 
garded  as  a  pure  development  of  empiricism,  his  analyses 
of  cause  and  effect  and  of  substance,  bodily  and  mental. 
What  Hume  does  in  fact  is  to  elaborate  and  clarify  the  prop 
osition  already  laid  down  by  Locke,  that  between  a  great 
part  of  our  simple  ideas  no  logical  agreement  or  disagreement 
is  to  be  found.  In  interpreting  this  proposition,  however, 
Hume  invariably  follows  another  principle  which  also  he 
derived  from  Locke,  viz.,  that  in  order  to  make  valid  knowl- 
edge  possible,  such  logical  relations  must  be  found.  This 
proposition,  which  constituted  the  peculiar  form  of  Locke's 
rationalism,  is  as  persistently  present  in  the  so-called  empir 
ical  parts  of  Hume's  philosophy  as  in  the  parts  already 
1  Bk.  I,  Pt.  II,  §§  2  and  3;  pp.  29ff. 


54  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

examined.  We  shall  now  examine  briefly  the  logical  frame 
work  of  Hume's  arguments  on  cause  and  effect,  bodily  sub 
stance,  and  personal  identity. 

The  course  of  Hume's  argument  is  in  general  the  same  in 
each  of  the  categories  examined.     He  first  shows  that  it     . 
cannot  be  derived  from  reason  and  then  the  manner  in  which 
it  does  arise  from  the  imagination.     Accordingly,  the  first 
step  in  his  analysis  of  cause  and  effect  is  to  show  that  the 
relation  is  not  demonstrative;  it  is  impossible  to  prove  that 
every  event  must  have  a  cause.1    The  chapter  really  centers 
about  a  bit  of  negative  criticism  of  the  kind  in  which  Hume 
excelled,  his  exposure  of  the  fallacy  in  the  arguments  of 
Hobbes,  Locke,  and  Clarke  to  prove  the  necessity  of  causes. 
Aside  from  these  criticisms,  Hume's  own  argument  is  exceed 
ingly  simple.     It  consists  in  pointing  out  that  as  the  ideas 
of  cause  and  effect  are  distinct  and  therefore  separable,  it  is 
impossible  to  proceed  from  one  idea  as  cause  to  another  idea 
as  effect.     No  intuitive  relationships  exist  which  enable  us 
to  make  this  transition  deductively.     Hence,  Hume  con-! 
Deludes,  cause  and  effect  cannot  arise  from  reason;  it  must;  r 
therefore  arise  from  imagination.     This  argument,  which 
recurs  again  and  again,  gives  us  the  clearest  insight  into  the 
form  of  Hume's  system,  i  Only  one  test  of  rationality  is 
contemplated,   namely,   the   possibility  of  discovering  im 
plications  by  the  mere  inspection  and  comparison  of  ideas. 
A  category  not  established  by  this  test  is  attributed  to  the 
imagination,  and  what  arises  from  the  imagination  is  de-    * 
void  of  validity.    The  argument  is  the  baldest  form  of  dis 
junction;  it  leaves  no  place  for  degrees  of  validity  or  distinc 
tions  of  method.    Since  it  is  manifestly  impossible  to  justify 
cause  and  effect  as  a  comparison  of  ideas,  this  is  enough  in 
%  itself  to  condemn  causality.    The  conclusion  is  reached  not 
'  by  the  empirical  analysis  of  cause  and  effect  but  by  the  fact 
that  no  analysis  of  cause  and  effect  can  bring  it  into  line 
with  the  pre-conceived  principle  that  knowledge  is  nothing 
but  the  perception  of  relations  between  ideas. N 

The  point  is  made  more  clear  when  we  examine  Hume's 
iBk.I,Pt.III,§3;pp.78ff. 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  55 

account  of  the  empirical  origin  of  cause  and  effect.     If  we 
analyze  particular  instances  of  causes  and  effects,  we  can 
detect  that  the  cause  is  contiguous  to  the  effect  and  prior 
to  it  in  time;  in  addition,  we  attribute  necessity  to  the  rela 
tion  but  in  particular  cases  no  ground  for  this  necessity 
appears.    All  that  can  be  seen  beyond  contiguity  and  priority 
is  that  the  relation  is  attributed  to  objects  which  are  con 
stantly  conjoined.     Hume  therefore  infers  that  the  idea  of 
necessary  connection  is  the  effect  of  the  repetition  of  these 
conjunctions.     It  is  a  habit  of  the  imagination,  the  result 
of  custom.1    Now  it  appears  self-evident  to  Hume  that  rep 
etition  can  have  no  relevance  to  the  validity  of  the  relation. 
For  this  validity,  if  it  existed  at  all,  being  detected  by  a 
comparison  of  the  idea  of  the  cause  with  that  of  the  effect, 
would  be  as  perceptible  in  the  first  instance  as  in  the  thou 
sandth.     On  the  other  hand,  if  the  relation  cannot  be  de 
tected,  no  number  of  repetitions  contributes  to  its  validity; 
repetition  contributes  only  to  the  strength  of  the  habit.    The 
dilemma  is  perfectly  plain:  Hume's  view  of  knowledge  is 
such  that  the  enumeration  of  instances  is  perfectly  irrelevant; 
he  is  of  course  quite  right  when  he  says  that  geometry  does 
not  prove  its  theorems  by  observing  a  thousand  circles  and 
summating  the  observations.    On  the  other  hand,  his  anal 
ysis  of  cause  and  effect  is  confined  to  cases  in  which  the 
enumeration  of  instances  is  not  only  relevant  but  substan 
tially  the  sole  method  possible.    Clearly  it  is  a  foregone  con 
clusion  that,  if  this  procedure  is  judged  by  a  standard  derived 
from  a  quite  different  procedure,  the  result  must  be  scep 
ticism. 

In  order  to  grasp  the  peculiar  logic  of  Hume's  argument, 
it  is  necessary  to  perceive,  first,  that  his  method  consists  in 
placing  side  by  side  two  extremely  divergent  theories  of 
knowledge  and,  second,  that  these  two  theories,  in  so  far  as 
they  have  any  basis  in  fact,  are  interpretations  of  two 
scientific  procedures  which  in  turn  are  the  most  widely 
divergent  to  be  found.  On  the  one  hand,  Hume's  empiricism 
is  not  that  of  the  experimental  physical  sciences,  which  were 
1  Bk.  I,  Pt.  Ill,  §  6;  pp.  86ff. 


56  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

a  closed  book  for  him  as  for  Locke  and  Berkeley.  Exper 
iments  carefully  devised  to  offer  a  crucial  test  of  rival  rational 
explanations  are  in  no  wise  mere  enumerations  of  instances; 
as  Mill  observed  long  after,  despite  his  inherited  inclination 
to  identify  the  empirical  method  with  enumeration,  one  such 
experiment  may  be  worth  a  thousand  random  observations. 
The  certainty  reached  by  this  means  is  not  at  all  a  function 
of  the  number  of  observations.  The  enumeration  of  in 
stances  belongs  more  typically  to  those  social  sciences  in 
which  alone  Hume  and  his  English  predecessors  were  at 
home.  Even  here,  however,  it  is  epistemological  theory 
rather  than  scientific  practice  which  identifies  the  method 
with  enumeration  of  instances  pure  and  simple.  It  was  the 
peculiarity  of  English  empiricism  to  neglect  the  hypotheses 
by  which  enumeration  is  guided,  a  neglect  which  rendered 
the  English  theory  of  knowledge  seriously  one-sided  even 
where  it  is  most  clearly  applicable.  On  the  other  hand, 
Hume's  rationalism,  like  Locke's,  was  quite  false  as  a  theory 
even  of  pure  mathematics.  No  theorem  in  mathematics 
is  proved  by  the  mere  contemplation  of  ideas,  even  though 
the  most  extreme  claims  of  mathematics  to  the  character 
of  an  a  priori  science  are  admitted.  Both  Locke  and  Hume, 
therefore,  had  an  erroneous  notion  of  the  scientific  method 
which  they  conceived  to  be  the  only  valid  one.  They  had 
also  an  inadequate  though  not  altogether  an  erroneous  no 
tion  of  the  procedure  of  those  psychological  and  social 
sciences  of  which  alone  they  had  any  first-hand  experience. 
The  conclusions  of  Hume's  system  are  the  result  of  placing 
the  inadequate  view  of  one  method  beside  the  erroneous 
interpretation  of  the  other  and  comparing  them  in  the  light 
of  the  assumption,  common  to  all  theories  of  knowledge  of 
the  period,  that  one  method  alone  can  be  correct.1 

1  It  should  be  insisted  that  this  interpretation  of  Hume  in  no  sense 
denies  the  fruitfulness  of  his  analysis  of  cause  and  effect.  So  far  as  this 
was  empirical  it  was  indisputably  fruitful.  What  was  not  fruitful  was 
his  wholly  non-empirical  prejudice  against  his  own  analysis.  Instead  of 
regarding  the  enumeration  of  instances  as  justified  by  the  fact  that  for 
some  subject-matters  it  is  quite  indispensable,  he  discredits  it  by  a  pre- 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  57 

When  we  turn  to  Hume's  treatment  of  substance  we  find 
that  his  conclusions  are  determined  by  an  exactly  similar 
discrepancy  between  erroneous  ideal  and  inadequate  empir 
ical  analysis.  The  form  of  the  argument  is  precisely  identical 
with  that  already  used  in  reference  to  cause  and  effect.  The 
senses  do  not  show  us  body,  because  we  never  perceive  any 
thing  except  an  impression.  Moreover,  the  reason  does  not 
enable  us  to  prove  the  distinct  and  continued  existence  of 
body.  Hence  the  belief  must  be  entirely  owing  to  the  imag 
ination.1  As  the  argument  proceeds,  we  get  a  clearer  insight 
into  this  incapacity  of  the  reason;  we  can  see  what  substance 
would  have  to  be  in  order  to  be  valid  according  to  Hume's 
standard.  In  accordance  with  the  principle  used  throughout 
his  philosophy,  Hume  points  out  that  all  perceptions  are 
distinct  and  therefore  separable.  Each  perception  is  numer 
ically  identical  with  itself  and  distinct  from  every  other, 
however  similar  in  quality  they  may  be.  Our  successive 
perceptions  of  any  object  possess  these  two  properties  of 
numerical  diversity  and  qualitative  similarity.  As  often  as 
I  see  my  table,  I  see  the  same  shade  of  brown,  but  my  seeing 
it  at  one  time  is  numerically  distinct  from  seeing  it  at  an 
other,  if  any  other  perception  has  intervened  to  interrupt 
the  sight  of  the  table.  The  similarity  operates  upon  our 
imaginations  to  make  us  think  the  similar  impressions  are 
identical;  the  slightest  attention  to  reason  shows  us  that  two 
perceptions  separated  by  an  interval  cannot  be  one.  Our 
experience  being  hopelessly  at  odds  with  itself,  we  feign  an 
explanation  which  permits  us  to  satisfy  both  tendencies: 
we  attribute  the  identity  to  something  we  call  body,  which 
we  imagine  to  exist  continuously  and  independently  of  the 
perceptions,  while  we  attribute  the  interruptions  and  dis 
continuity  to  the  perceptions. 

The  burden  of  this  argument  evidently  falls  upon  what 
Hume  regards  as  the  irrationality  of  the  notion  of  identity 
as  used  of  substances.  It  is  neither  unity  nor  multiplicity: 

conception  of  what  the  method  ought  to  be,  though  the  preconceived 
method  has  no  application  at  all. 
*  Bk.  I,  Pt.  IV,  §  2;  pp.  i9iff. 


$8  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

not  unity,  for  the  proposition,  'A  body  is  itself/  cannot 
mean  anything  if  the  subject  and  predicate  are  indistinguish 
able;  not  multiplicity,  for  if  objects  are  different,  it  is  a  con 
tradiction  to  say  they  are  the  same.    Identity,  then,  is  "an 
idea  which  is  a  medium  betwixt  unity  and  number;"  it  means 
"the  invar iableness  and  uninterruptedness  of  any  object,  thro' 
a  suppos'd  variation  of  time."  1    Hume  at  once  proceeds, 
however,  to  the  conclusion  that  this  idea,  because  it  is  a 
medium  between  unity  and  multiplicity,  must  be  a  confusion 
of  them.     Since  different  impressions  are  different  and  not 
the  same,  "the  opinion  of  their  identity  can  never  arise  from 
reason,  but  must  arise  from  the  imagination."    The  supposed 
continued  existence  of  bodies  is  a  fictitious  identity,  since 
the  numerically  different  impressions  cannot  be  the  same, 
and  this  fictitious  identity  is  the  effect  of  the  resemblances 
between  the  interrupted  impressions.     Thus  after  showing 
that  identity  cannot  be  the  same  as  unity,  Hume  discred 
its  it  because  it  is  not  the  same.     The  object  is  not  a  pure 
unit   in  which   no    differences   are   discernible,   and   conse 
quently  its  supposed  identity  must  be  a  fiction,  while  the 
rational  ideal  of  identity  as  pure  unity,  though  it  never  has 
a  factual  existence,  is  the  only  sense  in  which  identity  has 
any  rational  justification.     The  sceptical  conclusion  man- 
\ifestly  rests  not  on  the  empirical  analysis  of  identity,  for 
/Hume's  analysis  is  unexceptionable  so  far  as  it  goes,  but 
jupon  an  unwillingness  to  abide  by  the  empirical  analysis 
Cafter  it  is  made.    The  category  of  substance,  as  Hume  says, 
"has  no  other  effect  than  to  remedy  the  interruptions  of  our 
perceptions;"  2  it  is  called  into  being  to  remove  a  contradic 
tion.     Surely  on  any  empirical  grounds  this  ought  to  be 
enough  to  justify  it,  but  the  truth  is  that  Hume  was  con 
vinced  in  defiance  of  experience  that  substance  ought  to  be 
a  'real  essence.'     Since  it  cannot  be  this,  it  must  be  "the 
monstrous  offspring  of  two  principles,"  a  bastard  born  of 
the  misalliance  of  reason  and  imagination.    As  in  the  case 
of  cause  and  effect,  it  is  the  dead  hand  of  Locke's  rationalism 
that  holds  back  the  fruit  of  Hume's  empirical  analysis. 
1  Bk.  I,  Pt.  IV,  §  ^\  p.  201.  2  Ibid.,  p.  209. 


RATIONALISM  IN  HUME'S  PHILOSOPHY  59 

Hume's  discussion  of  personal  identity  1  follows  so  closely 
the  treatment  of  bodily  substance  that  it  can  be  disposed  of 
in  a  few  sentences.  Here  also  the  empirical  analysis,  when 
allowed  to  stand  by  itself,  is  fruitful.  At  one  blow  Hume 
disposes  of  the  monstrous  assumption  that  a  category  so 
complex  as  personal  identity  is  to  be  justified  after  the  man 
ner  of  Descartes  and  Locke  by  the  appeal  to  an  isolated  in 
tuition.  He  shows  that  what  we  actually  mean  by  personal 
identity  involves  diversity  and  succession  in  relation,  that 
it  involves  '  sympathy  of  parts  to  a  common  end,'  and  that 
it  is  of  the  same  type  as  other  concepts,  such  as  the  state, 
in  which  a  functional  subordination  of  parts  is  implied.  That 
such  concepts  are  useful  and  even  indispensable  Hume  does 
not  doubt.  Nevertheless  the  identity  of  the  mind  "cannot 
run  the  several  different  perceptions  into  one  and  make  them 
lose  their  characters  of  distinction  and  difference  which  are 
essential  to  them,"  and  therefore  the  identity  is  fictitious; 
it  is  due  solely  to  a  confusion  of  relatedness  with  identity. 
It  apparently  did  not  occur  to  Hume  that  if  personal  iden 
tity  could  'run  the  different  perceptions  into  one,'  it  would 
have  lost  whatever  usefulness  it  had.  His  criticism  of  the 
concept  is  entirely  obsessed  by  the  preconception  that  a 
concept  is  not  justified  by  its  empirical  function  in  analyzing 
and  relating  phenomena  but  only  by  a  sort  of  esoteric,  logical 
self-evidence. 

In  conclusion,  then,  we  may  repeat  what  we  asserted  at 
the  beginning,  that  it  is  a  misconception  of  Hume's  system 
to  regard  it  as  showing  the  inevitable  logical  consequences  of 
empiricism.  Even  though  we  confine  ourselves  to  the  in 
adequate  empiricism  of  English  philosophy  in  the  eighteenth 
century,  it  is  not  true  to  say  that  Hume  was  an  empiricist 
pure  and  simple.  The  heritage  of  Cartesian  rationalism, 
in  the  emasculated  form  given  it  by  Locke,  runs  through  it 
all  and  at  every  turn  limits  the  fruitfulness  of  the  empirical 
principles.  The  later  history  of  English  thought  shows  that, 
even  on  the  narrow  ground  occupied  by  the  empiricism  of 
the  eighteenth  century,  these  principles  were  not  incapable 
iBk.I,Pt.IV,§6;pp.  25iff. 


60  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

of  great  development.  The  associational  psychology  was  in 
substance  an  extension  of  Hume's  method  of  empirical 
analysis  and,  in  spite  of  its  glaring  faults,  it  was  an  indis 
putable  contribution  to  the  empirical  study  of  mind.  Its 
achievements  are  not  to  be  separated  from  the  development 
of  the  Utilitarian  ethics  which,  again  allowing  for  all  its 
defects,  was  the  first  incontestably  modern  theory  of  moral 
phenomena  and  an  indispensable  instrument  in  the  progress 
of  liberal  political  theory  and  the  rise  of  economics.  If  it 
were  true  that  Hume's  scepticism  is  the  final  outcome  of 
empiricism,  these  facts  would  be  the  most  incomprehensible 
in  the  history  of  philosophy.  They  would  mean  nothing 
less  than  that  the  most  fruitful  applications  of  a  set  of  phil 
osophical  principles  were  made  after  the  ablest  exponent  of 
them  had  demonstrated  their  logical  futility.  So  fantastic 
an  hypothesis  is  quite  untenable.  If  Hume's  scepticism  was 
not  refuted  by  his  successors,  it  was  certainly  neglected. 
With  eminent  good  sense,  most  later  English  philosophers 
regarded  his  scepticism  as  irrelevant  and  devoted  them 
selves  to  the  elaboration  of  empiricism  in  those  social  sciences 
upon  which  English  philosophy  has  always  nourished  itself. 
The  final  scientific  fruition  of  these  methods  came  in  the 
biology  of  Charles  Darwin,  where  they  become  the  point  of 
departure  for  a  newer  and  more  adequate  empiricism.  On 
the  side  of  the  physico-mathematical  sciences  a  like  result 
was  achieved  in  the  long  run  through  the  effect  upon  Kant 
of  Hume's  empiricism,  though  Kant  also  struggled  more  or 
less  ineffectually  with  misconceptions  bred  of  rationalism. 
In  respect  to  both  departments  of  science,  the  final  outcome 
of  Hume's  philosophy  was  to  destroy  the  false  simplicity 
engendered  by  the  radically  non-empirical  prejudice  that 
one  simple  method  can  alone  possess  logical  validity,  though 
Hume  himself  remained  entangled  in  this  preconception  to 
the  last.  This  result  was  but  a  clearing  of  the  ground  for  a 
more  thorough-going  empiricism. 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE:  KANT 
RADOSLAV  ANDREA  TSANOFF 

IN  the  history  of  ethical  thought,  especially  since  Augus 
tine,  the  service  into  which  the  idea  of  human  freedom  has 
been  pressed  in  connection  with  the  problem  of  evil  has 
brought  the  libertarian  issue  into  the  very  heart  of  ethical 
inquiry  and  has  tended  to  make  the  problem  of  freedom  a 
distinctively  ethical  problem.  Freedom  and  determinism 
have  been  referred  traditionally  to  the  department  of  morals. 
It  is  the  purpose  of  this  paper  to  consider  whether  ethics  has 
anything  to  gain  by  identifying  itself  with  the  libertarian 
controversy,  indeed  whether  or  in  what  sense  freedom  can 
be  regarded  as  an  ethical  postulate  at  all.  To  that  end  we 
shall  inquire  into  the  precise  meaning  and  into  some  of  the 
implications  of  the  classical  theory  of  freedom  as  an  ethical 
postulate,  the  theory  of  Kant,  and  shall  then  consider  very 
briefly  the  bearing  which  the  results  of  this  inquiry  have 
upon  the  role  and  the  significance  of  freedom  as  a  notion  in 
ethics. 

I 

In  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  Kant  undertakes  to  explain 
and  establish  epistemologically  the  universal  validity  of 
scientific  laws  and  so  to  safeguard  science  from  the  embar 
rassment  in  which  Hume's  scepticism  had  placed  it.  The 
Transcendental  ^Esthetic  and  the  Transcendental  Analytic 
lead  to  the  conclusion  that  experience  is  inevitably  spatial- 
temporal.  The  categories  of  the  understanding  condition  the 
possibility  of  experience;  the  world  of  possible  experience  is 
a  necessarily  connected  world  in  space  and  time.  Things- 
in-themselves  are  of  negative  significance  for  knowledge; 
theoretical  reason  can  neither  describe  them  nor  deny  their 
reality,  since  by  definition  they  are  trans-experiential.  The 
universal  validity  of  the  laws  of  science  is  thus  based  on  the 


62  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

organizing  role  of  the  understanding,  which  makes  experience 
and  nature  possible. 

It  is  with  such  an  epistemological  background  that  Kant 
approaches  the  problem  of  freedom  in  the  third  antinomy 
of  the  Transcendental  Dialectic.  He  attempts  to  solve  this 
third  conflict  of  the  transcendental  ideas  by  showing  the 
compatibility  of  the  thesis  and  the  antithesis.  The  thesis 
declares:  "Causality,  according  to  the  laws  of  nature,  is  not 
the  only  causality  from  which  all  the  phenomena  of  the  world 
can  be  deduced.  In  order  to  account  for  these  phenomena 
it  is  necessary  also  to  admit  another  causality,  that  of  free 
dom."  *  Absolute  spontaneity  of  causes  is  thus  assumed  in 
order  to  avoid  the  endless  series  of  conditions  which  would 
make  the  completeness  of  the  world-system  impossible. 
The  antithesis,  on  the  other  hand,  asserts  that  everything 
in  the  world  takes  place  entirely  according  to  the  laws  of 
nature  and  that  there  is  no  freedom.  The  proof  of  the  an 
tithesis  is  unnecessarily  obscure;  stripped  of  involved  ver 
biage,  it  amounts  to  this:  a  free-acting  cause  cannot  be  an 
event  in  the  space-time  world  that  we  know,  since  that  world 
is  a  world  of  necessary  connection.  The  antithesis  thus 
merely  restates  the  conclusion  of  Kant's  own  epistemology. 

Kant  endeavors  to  overcome  the  conflict  by  reconciling 
the  thesis  and  the  antithesis :  that  is,  by  showing  that  theoret 
ical  reason  can  somehow  maintain  both  without  contradic 
tion.  Conceived  as  the  faculty  of  beginning  a  state  spon 
taneously,  "freedom  is  a  purely  transcendental  idea,  which, 
first,  contains  nothing  derived  from  experience,  and,  secondly, 
the  object  of  which  cannot  be  determined  in  any  experience; 
because  it  is  a  general  rule,  even  of  the  possibility  of  all 
experience,  that  everything  which  happens  has  a  cause,  and 
that  therefore  the  causality  also  of  the  cause,  which  itself  has 
happened  or  arisen,  must  again  have  a  cause.  In  this  manner 
the  whole  field  of  experience,  however  far  it  may  extend, 
has  been  changed  into  one  great  whole  of  nature."  But  Kant 
goes  on  to  say,  "as,  however,  it  is  impossible  in  this  way  to 
arrive  at  an  absolute  totality  of  the  conditions  in  causal 
1  Kr.  d.  r.  V.,  1781,  p.  444;  tr.  by  Max  Miiller,  p.  362. 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE  63 

relations,  reason  creates  for  itself  the  idea  of  spontaneity, 
or  the  power  of  beginning  by  itself,  without  an  antecedent 
cause  determining  it  to  action,  according  to  the  law  of  causal 
connection."  1     The   idea  of  freedom   is   created   by  pure 
theoretical  reason  for  the  purpose  of  arriving  at  an  absolute 
totality  of  the  conditions  in  causal  relations.    That  is  to  say, 
Kant  admits  the  claim  of  the  antithesis  and  then  proceeds 
to  make  room  for  freedom  by  demanding  absolute  complete 
ness  for  the  world-system.     In  doing  this,  however,  he  vi 
olates  the  first  condition  upon  which  the  antithesis  rests  its 
argument,  namely,  that  the  world  of  experience  is  not  an 
absolutely  complete   system,  but  a   system  of  uniformity 
in  which  any  event  A  is  regarded  as  the  effect  of  some  other 
event  B,  and  that  in  turn  the  effect  of  some  other  event  C, 
and  so  on  ad  indefinitum.    The  same  Kantian  epistemology 
which  makes  free  spontaneity  inadmissible  in  the  causal 
series  of  experience   precludes   the   notion  of  an   absolute 
totality  of  that  series.     Kant's  theory  of  experience,  there 
fore,  justifies  the  antithesis  of  the  third  antinomy,  since  it  is 
concerned  only  with  experience  and  knows  nothing  positive 
about  things-in-themselves.2 

All  empirical  libertarianism  has,  accordingly,  been  dis 
credited.  In  the  sphere  of  theoretical  philosophy,  freedom 
remains  only  as  an  abstract  notion  with  metaphysical  im 
plications,  and  Kant  is  satisfied  if  he  can  merely  entertain 
the  notion  of  freedom  without  logical  self-contradiction.  In 
deed,  this  indecision  in  which  the  theoretical  reason  leaves 
the  problem  is  precisely  in  line  with  Kant's  position,  since 
it  prepares  the  way  for  what  he  considers  the  true  and  real 
establishment  of  human  freedom,  which  properly  is  not  a 
theoretical  but  an  ethical  notion,  a  postulate  of  practical 
reason. 

1  KT-  d.  r.  V.,  1781,  p.  533;  tr.  by  Max  Miiller,  pp.  432f. 

2  This,  of  course,  is  Schopenhauer's  conclusion.     Cf.  in  this  connection 
Schopenhauer's  Werke,  Grisebach  Edition,  Vol.  I,  pp.  63 21.;  Haldane 
and  Kemp's  translation  of  The  World  as  Will  and  Idea,  Vol.  II,  pp.  niff. 
Cf.  also  the  present  writer's  Schopenhauer's  Criticism  of  Kant's  Theory  of 
Experience,  pp.  57ff. 


64  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

"If  freedom  is  to  be  a  property  of  certain  causes  of  phe 
nomena,  it  must,  as  regards  these,  which  are  events,  be  a 
faculty  of  beginning  them/row  itself  (sponte),  that  is,  without 
the  causality  of  the  cause  itself  beginning,  and  hence  with 
out  requiring  any  other  ground  to  determine  its  beginning. 
But  then  the  cause,  as  to  its  causality,  must  not  rank  under 
time-determinations  of  its  state;  that  is,  not  be  a  phenomenon, 
and  must  be  considered  as  a  thing  per  se,  and  its  effects  only 
as  phenomena.  If  we  can  think  such  an  influence  of  the 
things  of  understanding  (Verstandesweseri)  on  phenomena 
without  contradiction,  then  natural  necessity  will  attach 
to  all  connexion  of  cause  and  effect  in  the  sensuous  world, 
but,  on  the  other  hand,  freedom  can  be  granted  to  such 
cause,  as  is  itself  not  a  phenomenon  (though  the  basis  of  one). 
Nature  therefore  and  freedom  can  without  contradiction  be 
attributed  to  the  very  same  thing,  but  in  different  rela 
tions — on  one  side  as  a  phenomenon,  on  the  other  as  a  thing 
per  se."  1 

This  is  a  typical  passage.  The  problem  becomes  one  of 
discovering  in  our  nature  some  fact  which,  transcending 
experience  in  its  implications,  would  necessarily  involve  free 
dom  as  a  rational  postulate.  This  fact  Kant  finds  in  the 
categorical  imperative,  in  the  unconditional  'ought.'  The 
moral  law  differs  from  the  laws  of  nature,  for,  while  these 
are  all  hypothetical  and  valid  only  within  their  particular 
spheres  of  reference,  it  possesses  unconditional  obligation. 
On  that  very  account  it  cannot  be  grounded  in  experience, 
since  experience,  as  Kant  has  defined  it,  is  a  system  of  rela 
tions  in  which  everything  depends  on  something  else.  The 
entire  content  of  experience,  accordingly,  is  relative  in  char 
acter,  and  thus  incapable  of  providing  a  fundamental  prin 
ciple  of  morals.  Nothing  can  be  called  good  without  qual 
ification  except  a  Good  Will,  that  is,  a  purely  rational  will, 
conceivably  autonomous,  operating  in  the  realm  of  pure 
ideas.  Such  a  will  recognizes  the  sublimity  of  its  rational 

1  Prolegomena,  Werke,  Vol.  IV,  p.  344;  tr.  by  Mahaffy  and  Bernard, 
pp.  1091.  All  references  to  Kant's  Werke  are  to  the  edition  by  the  Prussian 
Academy. 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE  65 

essence  but  it  also  feels  the  fetters  of  sense.  Hence  the  sig 
nificance  of  the  categorical  imperative.  "What  makes 
categorical  imperatives  possible  is  this,  that  the  idea  of  free 
dom  makes  me  a  member  of  an  intelligible  world,  in  con 
sequence  of  which,  if  I  were  nothing  else,  all  my  actions 
would  always  conform  to  the  autonomy  of  the  will;  but,  as  I 
at  the  same  time  intuite  myself  as  a  member  of  the  world  of 
sense,  they  ought  so  to  conform."  1 

Morality  thus  arises  out  of  the  conflict  between  our 
empirical  and  our  intelligible  characters.  The  categorical 
nature  of  moral  obligation  indicates  the  pure  rationality  of 
the  will  which  it  moves;  it  therefore  transcends  the  empirical 
world  of  necessity  and  implies  freedom.  But  its  imperative 
character,  the  very  idea  of  ought,  implies  the  uncongeniality 
of  the  sphere  of  sense-experience  in  which  the  ideally  free 
will  actually  operates.  Thus  the  one  fact  of  moral  obligation  \ 
logically  necessitates  the  postulation  of  human  nature  as  at 
once  determined  and  free,  determined  by  the  necessity  of 
the  phenomenal  nexus  in  which  it  is  involved,  yet  acting  ;i 
spontaneously  in  its  noumenal  capacity.  That  whichj 
theoretical  reason  could  only  conceive  as  a  mere  concept, — 
the  notion  of  a  two-faced  character  and  of  a  twofold  world, — 
practical  reason  has  now  demonstrated  as  a  certainty.  The 
oretically  we  are  not  prohibited  from  entertaining  the  notion 
of  freedom;  ethically  we  are  compelled  to  maintain  it,  if 
morality  is  to  have  any  significance.  This,  in  the  main,  is 
Kant's  theory  of  freedom  as  an  ethical  postulate. 

While  the  above  account  indicates  what  appears  to  be 
Kant's  distinctive  theory  of  freedom,  we  find  in  his  works 
a  variety  of  statements  suggesting  a  possible  vacillation  on 
Kant's  part  with  regard  to  the  problem  before  us.  It  would 
be  possible  to  interpret  Kant's  language  occasionally  as 
implying  the  belief  in  psychological  freedom  or  in  self- 
determinism;  but  psychological  freedom  is  out  of  harmony 
with  the  fundamental  tenor  of  Kant's  ethical  system,  for 
the  individual's  motives  are  themselves  involved  in  the 
intricate  nexus  of  conditioned  events  in  experience  and  can- 
1  Qrundlegung,  Werke,  Vol.  IV,  p.  454;  tr.  by  Abbott,  pp.  73f. 


66  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

not  provide  the  basis  for  an  ethical  doctrine  of  freedom  in 
the  Kantian  sense.  Kant  has  been  thoroughly  consistent 
in  tracing  the  strands  of  necessity  through  the  entire  fabric 
of  experience  and  has  left  no  room  for  psychological  freedom 
in  his  system.  He  distinctly  repudiates  it  in  the  second 
Critique.1  Again,  he  defines  freedom  as  "the  faculty  of  a 
cause  to  determine  itself  to  action,  untrammeled  by  sense 
conditions,"  and  as  "the  independence  of  causality  from  the 
conditions  of  space  and  time."  2  It  is  not  easy  to  ascertain 
the  precise  significance  of  such  definitions.  Does  Kant  mean 
to  imply  a  capacity  in  each  individual  of  freely  intruding 
into  the  causal  series,  that  is  to  say,  of  actually  producing 
empirical  effects  in  defiance  of  the  causal  system?  One 
would  hesitate  even  to  suggest  such  an  interpretation  were 
it  not  for  the  fact  that  Kant  himself,  in  a  passage  in  the 
second  Critique,  speaks  of  man's  capacity  to  have  left  undone 
an  action  that  he  has  performed,3  in  a  way  ominously  rem 
iniscent  of  the  old  scholastic  freedom  of  indifference.  This 
view  of  freedom,  however,  as  the  context  of  the  passage  in 
question  itself  clearly  shows,  is  so  obviously  out  of  place  in 
Kant's  philosophy  that  it  may  forthwith  be  dismissed. 

But,  if  the  possibility  of  beginning  a  new  causal  series 
within  or  alongside  of  the  phenomenal  nexus  is  thus  ruled 
out,  it  may  yet  be  possible  to  originate  spontaneously  the 
very  ground  of  causation.  Every  event  in  experience  may 
of  necessity  be  the  effect  of  a  cause,  and  still  the  causal  sys 
tem  itself  may  conceivably  be  grounded  in  a  spontaneous 
act  of  freedom.  This  point  of  view,  however,  reveals  a 
difficulty  regarding  the  relation  of  the  empirical  nature  of 
man  to  his  intelligible  character,  a  difficulty  which  seems  to 
cripple  Kant's  entire  argument.  It  may  be  stated  briefly 
thus:  Kant  calls  our  attention  to  a  Janus-like  personality/ 
one  face  turned  toward  the  phenomenal  world  of  necessary 

1  Kr.  d.  pr.  V.,  Werke,  Vol.  V,  pp.  93*?.;  tr.  by  Abbott,  pp.  iS/ff. 

2  Observations  1533,  1541  (Kant's  Reflexionen).    I  quote  from  Professor 
Felix  Adler's  paper,  "A  Critique  of  Kant's  Ethics,"  Mind,  N.  S.,  Vol.  XI, 
1902,  p.  168. 

3  Kr.  d.  pr.  V.,  Werke,  Vol.  V,  p.  98;  tr.  by  Abbott,  p.  191. 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE  67 

connection,  the  other  freely  directing  its  gaze  toward  the1 
eternal  course  of  reason.  Man's  empirical  character  is 
thoroughly  involved  in  the  causal  order,  as  truly  subject  to 
scientific  calculation  as  are  the  orbits  of  the  celestial  bodies, 
while  his  intelligible  character  is  purely  rational,  sponta 
neously  active  in  the  noumenal  realm  of  ideas,  sublimely 
independent  of  the  causal  system,  and  indeed  originating 
the  very  basis  of  that  system.  And  yet  these  two  charac 
ters,  each  of  which  is  the  negation  of  the  other,  are  not  to  be 
regarded  as  being  out  of  touch.  The  intelligible  character 
is  hampered  by  the  empirical;  wherefore  arises  the  categor 
ical  imperative  of  unconditional  obligation,  'Thou  oughtest'; 
but  ideally  the  intelligible  character  also  dominates  the 
empirical,  whence  springs  the  moral  faith,  'Thou  canst.' 

Kant's  own  reasoning  apparently  leads  from  the  fact  of 
the  categorical  imperative  to  the  conclusion  of  the  dual 
character  of  man  and  the  postulate  of  transcendental  free 
dom.  We  need  not  press  here  the  question  whether,  in  de 
riving  these  two  conceptions,  he  is  involved  in  a  circle,  a 
charge  against  which  he  defends  himself  in  the  Grundlegung.1 
The  real  difficulty  is  to  be  found  in  this,  that  Kant,  while 
upholding  the  unquestioned  reality  of  the  moral  fact  upon 
which  he  bases  his  theory,  nevertheless  claims  as  an  argument 
of  the  first  importance  that  his  theory  of  transcendental  free 
dom  is  not  inconsistent  with  the  demands  of  theoretical 
reason.  Has  he  succeeded  in  establishing  this  latter  conten 
tion?  Can  the  mind  think  of  a  timeless,  free,  intelligible 
character  directing  and  affecting  a  temporal,  determined, 
empirical  character?  If  it  does  actually  affect  it,  it  must  do 
so  in  the  medium  of  time,  which  is  the  only  medium  in  which 
the  empirical  character  can  be  affected,  and  in  that  case  it 
must  itself  enter  into  the  temporal  series,  which  it  by  def 
inition  transcends.  And  if,  starting  the  other  way,  we  con 
ceive  of  the  intelligible  character  as  affecting  the  empirical 
without  descending  from  its  timeless  sublimity,  then  we  are 
forced  to  the  conclusion  that  the  empirical  character,  existing 
in  time,  points  to  and  demands  an  over-phenomenal,  time- 
1  Werke,  Vol.  IV,  p.  453 ;  tr.  by  Abbott,  p.  72. 


68  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

less  explanation,  a  claim  diametrically  opposite  to  the  con 
clusion  of  Kant's  epistemology.  In  other  words,  Kant's 
theory  of  the  empirical  and  the  intelligible  character,  which 
is  involved  in  his  notion  of  transcendental  freedom,  does  con 
tain  a  theoretical  self-contradiction  so  long  as  we  regard  the 
intelligible  character,  and  thus  freedom,  as  in  any  way 
actually  operative  in  human  conduct. 

Moreover,  the  intelligible  character  itself,  just  because  of 
its  pure  rationality,  appears  incompatible  with  freedom  in 
any  intelligible  sense.  That  which  the  ideally  good  will 
would  do,  and  which  the  good  will,  hampered  by  the  im 
pediments  of  sense-experience,  ought  to  do,  is  by  no  means 
absolutely  elective.  It  is  the  inevitable  expression  of  the] 
will's  rationality.  Kant  has  pushed  the  entire  discussion! 
one  step  back,  but  there  the  same  issue  confronts  us.  In 
what  sense  is  the  individual  free,  if  his  empirical  character 
is  a  link  in  the  causal  chain,  and  his  intelligible  character  the 
immutable  manifestation  of  eternal  reason?  Thus  consid 
ered,  Kant's  theory  not  only  does  not  overthrow  determin 
ism,  but  indeed  reaffirms,  enlarges  upon,  and  universalizes 
it.  Psychological  determinism  denies  the  actuality  of  free 
dom  in  the  world  of  experience.  This  denial  Kant's  epis 
temology  validates.  To  this  conclusion  of  empirical  deter 
minism  of  the  antithesis  in  the  third  antinomy,  Kant  now 
virtually  adds  a  metaphysical  theory  which  excludes  free 
dom  from  the  eternal  essence  of  human  nature,  with  which 
essence  the  empirical  determinist  has  not  concerned  himself 
at  all. 

All  this  contention,  be  it  repeated,  holds  good  only  if  we 
interpret  Kant  to  mean  that  the  intelligible  character  is 
actually  operative  in  the  world  of  experience.  A  Kantian 
libertarian  may  protest,  however,  that,  in  proceeding  from 
the  standpoint  of  theoretical  reason,  we  have  violated  Kant's 
chief  injunction.  This  protest  is  entirely  just,  for  Kant  up 
holds  the  primacy  of  practical  reason  and  insists  that,  if  we 
start  from  experience  and  theoretical  reason,  we  can  never 
prove  the  actuality  of  freedom,  which  is  a  postulate  of  prac 
tical  reason  grounded  in  the  moral  fact  of  categorical  obliga- 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE  69 

tion.  But  the  violation  of  Kant's  injunction  is  also  justified 
because  of  his  contention  that  his  doctrine  of  trans 
cendental  freedom  does  not  involve  any  theoretical  con 
tradiction. 

Once  more  we  are  advised  to  stand  upon  the  solid  rock 
of  the  categorical  imperative,  the  one  immutable  support 
of  any  true  theory  of  morality  and  freedom.  Let  us  accord 
ingly  examine  our  problem  with  reference  to  this  proposed 
base.  Is  this  ' ought'  a  fact  of  consciousness?  That  would 
hardly  do,  for  in  such  a  case  it  would  be  empirical,  psycholog 
ical,  and  therefore  unfit  to  serve  as  a  foundation  for  a  cat 
egorical  ethics  or  for  a  purely  rational  theory  of  freedom. 
But  if  it  is  not  a  fact  of  consciousness,  what  is  it?  How  did 
Kant  arrive  at  it?  How  can  it  be  instrumental  in  uncon 
ditionally  compelling  human  conduct  unless  it  relates  itself 
to  the  empirical  consciousness?  And  how  can  it  do  that  if 
it  completely  transcends  it?  Again,  how  is  Kant's  argument 
to  appeal  to  the  man  who,  unfortunately,  discovers  no  such 
categorical  imperative  in  himself?  It  is  readily  granted  that 
one  would  be  responsible  if  he  transgressed  the  categorical 
imperative  which  he  recognized  in  his  moral  nature.  But 
how  is  one  to  be  held  responsible  for  the  absence  from  his 
nature  of  the  imperative  which  is  professedly  the  very  source 
and  ground  of  all  responsibility?  To  be  sure,  Kant  claims 
as  the  unique  characteristic  of  his  categorical  imperative 
that  it  precludes  any  questions  as  to  its  justification  or  origin. 
An  orthodox  Kantian  rules  all  the  above  questions  out  of 
court.  But  what  is  an  orthodox  Kantian  to  say  to  a  man 
who  does  not  even  understand  the  language  of  the  categorical 
ethics  ?  Is  he  to  cast  him  into  the  outer  darkness  as  a  creature 
forever  incapable  of  morality?  In  that  case  the  creature 
thus  cast  out  may  turn  and  openly  challenge  the  categorical 
excommunicator,  branding  him,  Nietzsche-wise,  as  morally 
diseased.  In  such  a  conflict  one  is  at  a  loss  to  think  of  a 
possible  arbiter.  Or  is  there  a  way  in  which  a  man  may 
finally  be  led  to  a  recognition  of  this  categorical  fact?  Then 
it  would  seem  that  the  recognition  of  the  categorical  im 
perative  can  be  attained  by  the  empirical  path,  which  fact 


70  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

would  deprive  Kant's  ethical  theory  of  its  unconditional 
foundation. 

There  is  no  refuge  from  this  dilemma  in  any  appeal  to  the 
general  consciousness  of  responsibility.  It  is  true  that  the 
average  human  being  is  inclined  to  accept  praise  or  blame  for 
his  actions,  but  this  tendency  in  human  nature  is  itself  after 
all  an  empirical  fact,  and  its  analysis  can  yield  ethical  truth 
only  to  him  who  does  not  reject  an  empirically  grounded 
ethics.  To  the  moralist  who  turns  his  back  on  experience 
the  sense  of  responsibility  may  be  the  utterance  of  the  moral 
'ought'  of  the  homo  noumenon;  but,  the  unbeliever  rejoins, 
it  may  with  equal  probability  be  the  last  vestige  of  super 
stition.  Men  considered  themselves  responsible  and  were 
praised  or  blamed  by  others  for  things  which  the  progress 
of  human  knowledge  has  shown  to  be  mere  illusions  of  ig 
norance.  We  no  longer  burn  witches  for  starting  pestilences, 
nor  do  we  burn  candles  to  saints  and  holy  men  for  blessing 
our  crops.  Science  is  weaving  more  and  more  closely  the 
fabric  of  causal  connections.  Whether  it  can  banish  from 
the  consciousness  of  man  the  sense  of  responsibility  itself 
is  not  a  matter  to  prophesy  about,  but  assuredly  it  is  a 
possible  alternative  which  can  be  accepted  or  rejected  only 
on  the  basis  of  experience.  At  any  rate,  few  theories  leave 
moral  responsibility  in  so  ambiguous  a  position  as  Kant's 
doctrine  of  the  empirical  and  the  intelligible  character. 
How  can  an  intelligent  man  regard  himself  in  any  way 
'responsible'  (in  the  Kantian  sense)  for  an  act  which,  on 
its  empirical  side,  is  a  necessary  link  in  a  causal  chain  in 
which  he  himself  is  thoroughly  entangled  and,  on  its  nou- 
menal  side,  is  the  expression  of  his  intelligible  character, 
which  is  the  inevitable  manifestation  of  eternal  reason? 
These  are  some  of  the  difficulties  in  which  the  notion  of  the 
categorical  imperative  is  involved;  they  show  the  actual 
uncertainty  of  the  supposedly  unquestionable  fact  upon 
which  Kant  depends  for  the  basis  of  his  whole  theory  of 
transcendental  freedom. 

It  thus  appears  that,  if  we  interpret  Kant's  freedom  as 
actual  and  the  intelligible  character  as  truly  influencing  the 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE  71 

empirical, — that  is  to  say,  if  we  regard  Kant's  moral  law  as 
indeed  legislating  in  the  realm  of  human  conduct, — we  are 
involved  in  radical  inconsistencies  from  which  no  escape 
seems  possible.  It  has  also  been  seen  that  such  an  inter 
pretation  of  Kant's  theory  not  only  does  not  overthrow 
scientific  determinism,  but  indeed  reaffirms  and  universal 
izes  it  and  provides  it  with  a  metaphysical  substructure. 
If  we  are  bound  in  search  of  freedom,  therefore,  we  seem 
compelled  to  accept  the  other  interpretation  to  which  Kant's 
elastic  theory  lends  itself,  namely,  that  the  ideas  of  the  moral 
law  and  transcendental  freedom  are  not  to  be  regarded  as 
certainties  but  only  as  practical  postulates.  We  are  to  act 
as  if  we  were  legislators  in  the  moral  world.  That  is  to  say, 
we  have  been  forced  to  reject  as  possible  alternatives  empir 
ical  freedom  of  choice,  the  actual  power  of  spontaneously 
inaugurating  a  causal  series,  or  even  of  freely  originating  the 
basis  of  the  system  of  necessity  itself.  We  ask  now,  not 
whether  one's  acts  are  the  acts  of  a  free  man,  but  whether 
his  attitude  towards  his  acts  is  the  attitude  of  a  free  man. 

In  this  sense  freedom  is  not  the  characteristic  of  certain 
acts,  of  certain  specific  events,  nor  yet  does  it  refer  to  a  nou- 
menal  substrate  of  the  entire  causal  series.  It  expresses 
itself  rather  in  a  certain  point  of  view  from  which  we  may 
regard  every  act  of  ours.  So  Kant  himself  wrote  in  the 
Prolegomena:  "I  may  say  without  contradiction:  that  all 
actions  of  rational  beings,  so  far  as  they  are  phenomena 
(occurring  in  any  experience),  are  subject  to  the  necessity 
of  nature;  but  the  same  actions,  as  regards  merely  the  ra 
tional  subject  and  its  faculty  of  acting  according  to  mere 
Reason,  are  free."  *  We  may  regard  our  every  act  as  if 
it  were  the  act  of  a  free  rational  will.  Our  very  rationality 
would  show  us,  on  every  occasion,  that  such  is  not  the  case; 
but  the  ethical  assertion  of  our  freedom  in  the  face  of  actual 
necessity  changes  our  whole  attitude  toward  our  acts  and 
thus  elevates  us;  we  become,  if  not  legislators  and  executives 
in  the  field  of  human  conduct,  at  least  its  ethical  judges. 
Our  acts  are  what  they  are  but  we  are  free  in  that  we  may 
1  Werke,  Vol.  IV,  p.  345;  tr.  by  Mahaffy  and  Bernard,  p.  in. 


72  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

rise  above  our  acts  and  pronounce  judgment  upon  them. 
We  may  thus  ideally  raise  our  very  acts  from  the  level  of 
necessity  to  the  plane  of  freedom.  But  only  ideally,  only  as 
a  postulate  of  practical  reason  is  transcendental  freedom 
admissible.  In  the  same  way  as  Epictetus,  though  in  shack 
les,  was  yet  a  free  man,  so  our  ethical  will  may  perform  its 
part  in  the  necessary  machinery  of  human  action  and  yet 
maintain  towards  it  an  attitude  of  true  liberty. 

This  is  a  complete  swing  of  the  pendulum  of  argument; 
from  the  freedom  of  the  act  we  have  passed  to  the  freedom 
of  the  agent,  or  rather  to  his  ideally  free  attitude.  It  would 
be  misunderstanding  Kant,  however,  if  we  said  that  such  a 
moral  agent  recognizes  his  acts  as  necessarily  determined, 
yet  comforts  himself  with  his  idea  of  being  free  anyhow.  No, 
it  is  the  empirical  subject  that  feels  the  pressure  of  necessity; 
the  moral  will  manifests  its  morality  precisely  in  this  attitude 
of  freedom  towards  its  acts.  That  is  its  ethical  essence. 
Our  acts  are  the  expression  and  inevitable  result  of  our  being; 
operari  sequitur  esse.  We  actually  do  what  we  must  do,  what 
we  cannot  help  doing.  But  our  ethical  attitude  towards  our 
conduct  is  free,  in  the  sense  that  we  evaluate  and  pronounce 
judgment;  we  ought  to  act  as  if  we  were  free  agents.  This 
seems  to  be  the  last  form  which  Kant's  theory  of  transcen 
dental  freedom  assumes. 

Yet  how  is  even  this  attitude  of  the  will  towards  its  acts 
intelligibly  free?  If  this  attitude  is  essential  to  all  moral- 
rational  beings,  as  Kant  claims,  then  it  is  hard  to  see  in  what 
sense  it  could  be  regarded  as  spontaneous.  For  if  it  is  the 
essence  of  our  moral  nature  to  judge  what  we  ought  to  do 
in  accordance  with  the  idea  of  the  moral  law,  then  our  judg 
ment  of  ought  is  itself  a  must;  our  ethical  will  'freely'  judges 
in  the  way  in  which  it  eternally  must  judge.  And  this  must 
into  which  the  ethical  ought  has  changed  is  in  no  way  ge- 
nerically  different  from  the  must  of  the  scientific  law.  The 
scientific  law  formulates  relations  which  express  the  inev 
itable  coherence  of  organic  experience.  The  maxim  of  the 
moral  will,  its  categorical  imperative,  is  likewise  the  for 
mulated  expression  of  its  inevitably  rational  character.  On 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE  73 

the  other  hand,  should  we  refuse  to  admit  Kant's  claim  that 
this  'free'  attitude  of  the  agent  is  essential  to  human  nature, 
Kant  would  be  confronted  with  the  dilemma  encountered 
above  in  connection  with  the  categorical  imperative;  he 
would  be  forced  either  to  seek  uncertain  refuge  in  the  rel 
ativism  of  empiricist  ethics  or  risk  abandoning  his  whole 
position. 

Kant's  so-called  theory  of  freedom  is  indeed,  in  spite  of 
Kant,  virtually  a  theory  of  determinism.  It  validates  the 
contention  of  the  antithesis  in  the  third  antinomy.  Regarded 
as  actually  originating  the  timeless  basis  of  the  causal  series, 
it  involves  us  in  insuperable  difficulties  and,  in  its  implica 
tions,  points  not  to  actual  freedom  but  to  what  is  almost 
fatalism.  Interpreted,  on  the  other  hand,  as  an  ethical 
attitude,  an  fas  if,'  freedom  becomes  a  defiantly  resigned 
consciousness  of  determinism. 

II 

The  first  radical  defect  of  Kant's  ethical  system  is  due  to 
his  very  conception  of  the  scope  and  of  the  role  of  morality. 
A  morality  which  seeks  its  basis  above,  that  is,  apart  from, 
the  world  of  possible  experience,  is  a  morality  which,  in  its 
first  chapter,  would  appear  free  from  the  impediments  of 
space-time  necessity,  and  which  on  that  account  would  admit 
of  a  more  sublime  statement  than  is  possible  in  the  case  of 
a  morality  grounded  in  experience.  But  this  apparent  free 
dom  from  empirical  entanglements,  so  sublime  in  prospect, 
shows  itself  illusory  in  the  last  chapter.  A  morality  exalted 
above  experience  finds  the  noumenal  dignity  of  its  laws  im 
paired  by  the  fact  that  they  fail  to  have  any  meaning  in  the 
very  sphere  in  which  they  are  to  apply.  Transcending  expe 
rience  and  yet  not  conditioned  by  experience,  such  a  moral 
ity  has  itself  no  meaning  for  experience  and  is  therefore 
an  illusory  morality.  The  'as  if  of  Kant's  system  means 
either  too  little  or  too  much:  The  moral  law  either  applies 
really  in  the  empirical  sphere,  in  which  case  the  description 
of  the  moral  law  and  of  the  empirical  sphere  must  be  revised 
so  as  to  make  possible  their  organic  relation;  or  else  the  moral 


74  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

law  does  transcend  the  empirical  sphere,  in  which  case  its 
4  as  if  application  to  experience  is  the  naive  illusion  of  our 
moral  consciousness.  The  notion  of  freedom,  noumenally 
regarded,  is  seen  to  change  before  our  very  eyes  into  a  no 
tion  of  determinism.  Estimated  in  terms  of  our  experience, 
Kant's  ethics  is  too  remotely  sublime  to  affect  our  lives,  and 
his  freedom  too  elusive  to  explain  our  moral  strivings. 

Should  we,  accordingly,  read  all  noumerialism  out  of  Kant's 
ethics  and  find  its  true  core  in  the  empirical  consciousness  of 
duty  and  responsibility,  then  his  notion  and  his  treatment 
of  freedom  would  require  a  radical  revision.  The  problem 
of  bringing  Kant's  ethics  down  to  earth  in  a  way  consistent 
with  the  fundamental  spirit  of  the  Critical  Philosophy,— 
"the  Holy  Ghost  in  Kant," — is  a  problem  too  complex  to  be 
undertaken  here.  The  above  discussion  has  perhaps  thrown 
some  light  on  the  true  significance  of  freedom  as  a  notion  in 
ethics,  and  it  may  be  worth  while,  in  conclusion,  to  indicate 
that  significance  in  very  broad  outline. 

In  championing  freedom  as  a  sine  qua  non  of  morality  and 
in  thus  condemning  moral  inquiry  to  the  futilities  of  the 
freedom  controversy,  the  libertarians  have  been  to  a  large 
degree  responsible  for  the  barren  dogmatism  which  has  char 
acterized  so  much  of  ethical  thought.  The  Christian  doc 
trine  of  salvation,  requiring  the  recognition  of  the  reality  of 
evil  in  this  world,  required  also  that  it  be  not  laid  at  God's 
door  and  accordingly  demanded  freedom  as  a  prime  condi 
tion  of  explaining  the  ethical  course  of  man.  A  hoary  dog 
matism,  theological  in  its  origin,  which  isolated  man  from 
God  above  and  from  nature  about  him  and  treated  the  human 
soul  as  sui  generis  and  transcending  the  world  of  things, 
led  ethical  speculation  into  the  quandary  of  being  compelled 
to  treat  the  human  will  as  affecting  the  course  of  nature  and 
yet  remaining  unaffected  by  it  or  by  its  inadequately  con 
ceived  law-conforming  mechanism.  The  scientific  and  phil 
osophical  implications  of  this  dogmatism,  insufficiently 
appreciated  during  the  period  of  theological  domination  in 
European  thought,  became  increasingly  manifest  as  modern 
science  proceeded  to  establish  on  solid  foundations  the  con- 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE  75 

ception  of  the  world  as  a  law-conforming  system  and  to 
banish  the  notion  of  absolute  chance.  The  realization  of 
these  implications,  involving  ethics  in  the  conflict  between 
freedom  and  determinism,  and  indeed  making  the  issue  of 
this  conflict  vital  to  the  very  possibility  of  morality  and  of 
ethics,  resulted  in  an  entanglement  of  ethical  inquiry  with 
metaphysical  speculation  essentially  irrelevant  to  it  and 
thus  retarded  the  progress  of  ethics  as  a  possible  science. 
Kant's  treatment  of  morality  is  the  most  instructive  example^ 
of  the  futilities  to  which  vigorous  ethical  thought  is  con 
demned,  so  long  as  it  follows  the  insidious  bias  of  theological 
dogmatism  and  seeks  the  guarantee  of  freedom  in  a  morality 
transcending  the  world  of  possible  experience.  That  Kant,  $, 
the  practical  task  of  whose  epistemology  was  to  free  the 
mind  of  man  from  the  dogmatism  of  his  predecessors,  was 
himself  the  child  of  the  old  order  and  manifestly  unable  to 
overcome  its  bias  in  the  field  of  morals,  is  the  less  surprising 
when  we  consider  that  Schopenhauer  himself,  a  professed 
completer  of  Kant's  work  and  an  arch-enemy  of  theological 
ethics,  remained  under  the  sway  of  that  ethics  in  his  whole 
sale  adoption  of  Kant's  doctrine  of  the  empirical  and  the 
intelligible  character  and  of  some  of  the  most  confusing 
elements  of  Kant's  notion  of  freedom  involved  in  that  doc 
trine. 

With  the  realization  of  the  true  origin  of  dogmatic  liberta- 
rianism  in  ethical  theory,  however,  it  becomes  manifest  that 
the  conflict  in  ethical  theory  between  freedom  and  determin 
ism  is  but  a  stage,  perhaps  the  last  stage,  in  the  effort  of 
thought  to  realize  itself  as  self-consistent  and  law-conforming, 
and  it  becomes  apparent  also  that  the  issue  between  deter 
minism  and  indeterminism  is  not,  strictly  speaking,  a  dis 
tinctively  ethical  issue.  Moreover,  the  issue,  as  it  is  sharply 
conceived  in  ethics,  is  itself  unreal,  an  anachronism  in  morals, 
where  it  has  survived  owing  precisely  to  the  fact  that  the 
too  slowly  relaxing  pressure  of  theological  dogmatism  has 
kept  ethics  divorced  from  actual  experience. 

The  fundamental  metaphysical  problem  as  to  the  admis- 
sibility  of  the  absolutely  spontaneous  is  not  raised  here  at  all. 


76  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

If  it  can  still  be  regarded  as  a  problem,  it  is  certainly  not  a 
part  of  our  present  undertaking  to  attempt  its  solution. 
The  only  point  to  be  kept  in  mind  here  is  that  it  is  a  problem 
of  metaphysics,  the  solution  of  which  is  not  a  sine  qua  non 
of  scientific  ethical  inquiry.  By  this  I  do  not  mean  to  divorce 
ethics  from  metaphysics  or  from  theory  of  knowledge,  but 
I  do  mean  to  point  out  that  the  progress  of  ethical  science, 
in  this  as  in  other  respects,  requires  a  more  complete  libera 
tion  from  metaphysical  as  well  as  from  theological  dogma 
tism. 

The  genuine  problem  of  freedom  is  essentially  a  problem 
affecting  the  ultimate  description  of  the  universe:  Does  it 
or  does  it  not  involve  the  absolutely  spontaneous,  the  ab 
solutely  indeterminable?  To  the  solution  of  this  problem 
every  science  contributes,  and  the  deterministic  tenor  of 
modern  scientific  thought  is  accordingly  significant.  Ethics, 
like  every  other  science,  must  approach  its  material,  human 
conduct,  with  a  view  to  describing  its  actual  character,  with 
a  view  moreover  to  estimating  that  character  in  accordance 
with  the  criteria  revealed  in  the  process  of  description.  And 
in  such  a  process  of  concrete  ethical  thought,  the  notion  of 
the  absolutely  spontaneous  can  enter,  if  at  all,  only  in  so 
far  as  it  is  relevant  to  moral  valuation  proper.  That  is  to"1 
say,  freedom  can  be  entertained  as  a  possible  ethical  pos 
tulate  or  category  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  necessitated  by  char 
acteristically  ethical  notions,  such  as  responsibility,  praise 
and  blame,  or  moral  valuation  in  general.  An  ethical  theory 
which  passes  beyond  this  point  in  its  dealings  with  the  prob 
lem  of  freedom  is  an  ethical  theory  which  forces  itself  into  a 
metaphysical  issue  and  by  so  doing  frustrates  the  successful 
prosecution  of  its  own  task.  As  ethical  science  realizes  the 
extent  to  which  the  problem  of  freedom  is  relevant  to  its  own 
specific  inquiry,  it  realizes  the  necessity  of  analyzing  anew 
and  more  carefully  the  significance  of  the  notions  of  respon 
sibility,  praise  and  blame,  and  the  implications  of  conduct- 
evaluation!  It  then  appears  with  increasing  clearness  that* 
approval  and  condemnation  are  not  limited  to  the  field  of 
morals,  but  apply  intelligibly  in  fields  which  the  most  ardent 


FREEDOM  AS  AN  ETHICAL  POSTULATE  77 

libertarian  would  describe  in  deterministic  terms.  It  would 
be  dogmatic,  to  be  sure,  to  maintain  that  the  analysis  of 
responsibility  and  of  moral  valuation  generally  will  lead  to 
the  ethical  confirmation  of  a  deterministic  metaphysics. 
But.it  is  significant  that  the  scientific  tendency  in  recent 
ethics  is  one  of  comparative  indifference  towards  the  tradi 
tional  libertarian  controversy.  This  tendency  on  the  part  of 
contemporary  ethical  science  indicates  its  determination  to 
approach  its  own  distinctive  problems  unimpeded  by  dog 
matic  prepossessions  and,  by  a  distinctively  ethical  analysis 
of  the  experience  with  which  it  deals,  to  make  its  own  real 
contribution  to  the  metaphysical  solution  of  the  knotty 
problem  of  freedom. 


MILL  AND  COMTE 
NANN  CLARK  BARR 

THE  relation  of  Mill  to  Comte  is  of  special  significance  in 
the  attempt  to  define  Mill's  place  among  the  various  currents 
of  contemporary  thought  for  two  reasons:  First,  for  the 
obvious  reason  that  Mill  himself  refers  to  Comte  as  one  who 
has  exercised  profound  influence  over  his  mind;  but  secondly, 
on  evidence  of  a  more  internal  character,  because  the  two 
men  represent  two  widely  divergent  reactions  on  the  in- 
tellectualism  and  individualism  which  characterize  eight 
eenth  century  thought,  and  because,  from  fundamentally 
the  same  theory  of  the  nature  of  knowledge  in  relation  to  the 
world  of  experience  and  to  ultimate  reality,  they  arrive  at 
opposite  solutions  of  the  more  concretely  complex  problems 
of  man's  practical  relations,  moral  and  social,  to  the  human 
world.  As  Mill  puts  it  in  his  Autobiography,  they  agree  as 
logicians  but  not  as  sociologists. 

The  influence  of  Comte  stands  in  the  sharpest  possible 
contrast  to  the  influence  of  Bentham  on  Mill's  general  mental 
attitude.  Although  it  is  impossible  to  trace  a  single  line 
of  development  in  Mill's  thought,  which  contained  con 
flicting  and  unassimilated  tendencies  to  the  end,  it  is  perhaps 
the  point  of  crisis  in  his  mental  career  when  he  first  super 
imposed  on  the  analytic,  egoistic,  atomic,  discontinuous 
method  of  Bentham,  the  socialistic,  synthetic,  and  historical 
vision  of  Comte  and,  in  lesser  degree,  of  Coleridge,  as  rep 
resentatives  of  a  new  tendency  in  philosophy.  The  essays 
on  Bentham  and  Coleridge,  which  manifest  so  strong  a 
sympathy  with  what  Mill  himself  considered  the  spirit  of 
the  nineteenth  as  opposed  to  the  eighteenth  century,  ap 
peared  in  1838  and  1840  respectively,  after  the  publication 
of  the  first  two  volumes  of  Comte's  Positive  Philosophy  in 
1837.  Though  Coleridge  is  taken  as  the  type  of  the  new 


MILL  AND  COMTE  79 

movement,  he  represents  an  attitude  rather  than  a  system, 
and  it  is  to  Comte  that  we  must  look  for  specific  influence 
over  important  elements  of  Mill's  doctrine. 

When  in  a  letter  to  Comte  written  in  1841  Mill  announces 
his  withdrawal  from  his  adherence  to  Bentham,  "in  which  I 
was  brought  up  and  in  which  I  might  almost  say  I  was  born," 
he  overestimates  the  extent  of  the  rejection.  The  rift  which 
he  even  then  recognized  in  the  lute  of  his  new  discipleship 
was  not  closed,  as  he  confidently  hoped,  by  thorough  dis 
cussion,  but  became  wider  when  the  subject  was  not  scientific 
methods  in  general,  but  the  nature  and  extent  of  the  union 
and  subordination  of  individuals  in  and  to  the  whole  of 
society.  But  if  the  individualism  of  Bentham  may  be  traced 
in  that  hatred  of  "spiritual  despotism"  which  leads  Mill  to 
say  of  Comte's  work  that  "the  book  stands  as  a  monumental 
warning  to  thinkers  on  sociology  and  politics,  of  what  hap 
pens  when  once  men  lose  sight  in  their  speculations  of  the 
value  of  liberty  and  individuality,"  l  still  it  is  Bentham  with 
a  difference.  The  reduction  to  self-interest  of  all  the  motives 
which  guide  men  in  society  and  in  moral  conduct  is  modified 
by  Comte's  sense  of  the  inadequacy  of  laissezfaire  to  express 
the  solidarity  of  the  social  order  and  his  emphasis  on  the 
social  feelings  in  the  moral  life.  ^/ 

In  their  ideas  of  the  fundamental  basis  of  all  knowledge, 
Comte  and  Mill  stand  on  common  ground.  We  have  no 
knowledge  of  anything  but  phenomena.  To  attempt  to 
transcend  appearance,  either  by  searching  for  an  underlying 
substance  of  reality  or  by  seeking  a  genuine  cause  outside 
the  series,  which  produced  it,  is  fruitless.  We  can  .study 
the  'how,'  but  not  the  'why'  of  the  world;  we  can  observe 
Constant  Delations  JD£tween  facts,  which  we  formulate  as 
laws  of  resemblance  and  sequence^  these  generalizations  of 
the  way  things  work  are  the  utmost  we  can  attain  within 
the  limits  of  scientific  procedure.  This,  then,  is  the  pre 
supposition  from  which  both  Mill  and  Comte  set  out. 

Since  the^goal  of  .knowledge ^cannot  be  ultimate  truth,  but 
only  provisional,  working  truth,  the  object  cannot  be  to  seek 
1  Autobiography,  p.  212. 


8o  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

that  which  we  can  never  hope  to  reach;  it  must  have  its 
value  within  the  realm  of  phenomenal  experience.  The  aim 
is  practical.  Comte's  formula,  savoir  pour  prevoir,  expresses 
on  the  intellectual  side  what  the  utilitarian  criticism  of  moral 
acts  by  their  consequences  expresses  on  the  ethical  side.  This 
dealing  with  knowledge  as  instrumental  to  conduct  is  char 
acteristic  of  Mill's  whole  attitude;  the  study  of  the  past 
is  valuable  for  the  sake  of  the  lessons  of  guidance  which  it 
furnishes;  moral  judgment  depends  on  the  way  in  which 
an  act  takes  effect  in  the  world.  In  this  practical  anti- 
intellectualism,  the  subordination  of  knowledge  to  our  action 
and  reaction  on  environment,  Mill  can  go  the  whole  way 
with  Comte.  But  this  view  is  not  at  variance  with  the  in- 
tellectualism  which  places  the  speculative  intellect  at  the 
head  as  the  main  agent  in  the  progress  of  mankind,  as  the 
instrument  of  co-operation  which  by  its  method  and  standard 
unites  conflicting  passions.  "The  history  of  opinions  and  of 
the  speculative  faculty  has  always  been  the  leading  element 
in  the  history  of  mankind."  1 

If  the  theory  that  the  main  determining  cause  of  social 
progress  is  intellectual  activity,  so  that  the  state  of  knowl 
edge  and  the  prevalent  beliefs  give  the  clew  to  the  general 
character  of  an  age  or  a  people,  is  one-sided  and  lays  too 
exclusive  an  emphasis  on  ideas,  this  is  by  way  of  counteract 
ing  that  subordination  of  the  intellect  to  the  heart  which 
led  Comte,  with  his  fantastic  fetich-mythology,  to  seem  to 
say,  "Believe  what  you  know  to  be  untrue,  for  the  sake  of 
the  emotional  stimulus."  If  Mill  over-emphasized  reason,  it 
was  that  it  might  be  given  due  importance  again  after  the 
over-emphasis  of  instinct  in  morality  by  Carlyle  and  the 
intuitionists  generally,  and  of  feeling  in  science  by  Comte  in 
his  later  writings.  "It  is  one  of  the  characteristic  prejudices 
of  the  reaction  of  the  nineteenth  century  against  the  eight 
eenth  to  accord  to  the  unreasoning  elements  in  human  nature 
the  infallibility  which  the  eighteenth  century  is  supposed  to 
have  ascribed  to  the  reasoning  element.  For  the  apotheosis 
of  reason  we  have  substituted  that  of  instinct."  2  Salvation, 
1  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  102.  2  The  Subjection  of  Women,  p.  6. 


MILL  AND  COMTE  8 1 

according  to  Mill,  lies  in  the  intellectualization  of  feeling  and 
instinct;  that  is,  in  the  study  of  psychology,  which  will  reveal 
the  true  structure  of  "what  is  bowed  down  to  as  the  inten 
tion  of  nature  and  the  ordinance  of  God." 

But  this  dependence  on  psychology  and  hence  on  in 
trospection  Comte  refuses  to  countenance.  His  phenom 
enalism  is  not  built  on  the  belief  that  the  mind  can  know  only 
its  own  states;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  just  these  which  it  cannot 
know.  Psychology  is  so  often  the  court  of  appeal  for  Mill 
because  it  is  the  key  to  the  inner  progress  of  character  in 
relation  to  circumstances,  while  for  Comte  it  is  only  the 
morphology  and  physiology  of  the  brain.  Comte's  rejection 
of  the  method  of  introspection  in  psychology  strikes  at  thej 
root  of  Mill's  reduction  of  logic  and  the  theory  of  knowledge 
to  psychological  terms,  which  is  a  fundamental  tenet  of  his 
philosophical  faith. 

In  rejecting  also  any  science  of  method  in  general,  that  is, 
any  canon  of  proof  which  is  universally  applicable,  Comte, 
in  Mill's  eyes,  makes  the  mistake  of  treating  the  philosophy 
of  science  as  consisting  only  of  the  methods  of  investigation. 
This  is  the  carrying  out  of  his  tendency  to  begin  with  the 
concrete  and  particular  which  is  his  characteristic  method  of 
treating  the  science  of  society.  But  this  is  not  enough. 
"We  are  taught  the  right  way  of  searching  for  results," 
says  Mill,  "but  when  a  result  has  been  reached,  how  shall 
we  know  that  it  is  proved?"  This  test  of  proof  is  the  func 
tion  of  logic.  Method,  according  to  Comte,  must  be  marked  ! 
out  for  each  science  separately;  there  is  no  method  apart 
from  its  specific  operations,  no  logic  except  in  its  application. 
Not  only  does  Mill  oppose  Comte's  subjugation  of  reason 
to  feeling,  but,  while  accepting  the  doctrine  that  usefulness 
is  the  sole  aim  of  knowledge  as  fundamentally  true,  he  does 
not  thereby,  like  Comte,  ban  all  research  which  has  not  an 
immediate  practical  bearing.  "No  respect  is  due  to  any 
employment  of  the  intellect  which  does  not  tend  to  the  good 
of  mankind."  1  Thus  far  there  is  agreement.  But  Mill  does 
not  demand  that  truth  shall  have  proved  its  usefulness  before 
1  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  172. 


82  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

it  is  accepted;  rather  he  has  faith  that  the  truth,  however 
remote  it  may  seem  from  life,  belongs  to  a  continuous  reality 
which  reaches  down  to  human  concerns.  Therefore  knowl 
edge  may  be  sought  for  its  own  immediate  sake;  the  world 
will  some  time  find  use  for  it;  it  will  not  forever  remain 
isolated  but  will  take  its  place  in  the  scheme  of  things.  Un 
expected  applications  of  pure  science  teach  us  that,  while 
some  truths  are  of  more  certain  and  present  utility  than 
others,  nobody  can  predict  what  may  be  useful:  "Who 
can  affirm  positively  of  any  speculations,  guided  by  right 
scientific  methods,  on  subjects  really  accessible  to  the 
human  faculties,  that  they  are  incapable  of  being  put  to 
use?"  l 

But  however  arbitrarily  Comte  may  define  the  limits  of 
the  exercise  of  the  cognitive  function,  he  is  yet,  in  Mill's 
opinion,  the  greatest  living  authority  on  scientific  methods 
in  general.  Though  we  cannot  arrive  at  non-phenomenal 
causes  of  the  phenomenal  world,  causality  in  another  sense 
is  universally  present  and  is  the  basis  of  all  our  scientific 
judgments.  The  cause  which  we  seek  in  order  that  we  may 
control  the  effect  or  adapt  ourselves  to  it  is  a  link  in  a  chain 
of  sequences.  This  conception  of  causality  as  the  observed 
succession  of  invariable  antecedents  is  common  meeting 
ground  for  Comte  and  Bentham  and  James  Mill,  though  all 
three  err  in  failing  to  distinguish  between  merely  invariable 
and  unconditional  invariable  sequences.  So  conceived,  the 
reign  of  law  is  universal:  "All  phenomena  without  exception 
are  governed  by  invariable  laws  with  which  no  volition, 
either  natural  or  supernatural,  interferes."  2  Man  takes  his 
place  in  the  natural  world  as  the  object  of  inductive  study 
and  in  the  terms  of  this  naturalistic  view  a  social  science 
correlative  with  the  other  natural  sciences  is  possible.  For 
social  phenomena  conform  to  the  same  invariable  conditions 
as  physical  phenomena  and  can  be  reduced  to  as  firmly  co 
ordinated  and  coherent  a  body  of  doctrine:  "The  method 
proper  to  the  science  of  society  must  be,  in  substance,  the 
same  as  in  all  other  sciences."  3 

1  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  173.     -  Ibid.,  p.  12.     3  Ibid.,  p.  83. 


MILL  AND  COMTE  83 

In  this  statement  of  the  problem  Mill  concurs.  And  he 
regards  as  mere  difference  in  order  of  procedure  what  at 
first  looks  like  a  more  formidable  disagreement.  For  Mill 
holds  that  "social  science  must  be  deduced  from  the  general 
laws  of  human  nature,  using  the  facts  of  history  merely  for 
a  verification."  l  As  social  causes  "cannot  have  been  known 
by  specific  experience,  they  must  have  been  learnt  by  deduc 
tion  from  the  principles  of  human  nature.  .  .  .  Nor,  in 
fact,  will  the  experimental  argument  amount  to  anything 
except  in  verification  of  a  conclusion  drawn  from  those  gen-  - 
eral  laws."  2  On  the  other  hand,  as  expounded  by  Mill, 
Comte's  view  is,  that  "as  society  proceeds  in  its  develop 
ment,  its  phenomena  are  determined  more  and  more,  not 
by  the  simple  tendencies  of  universal  human  nature,  jry.v 
but  by  the  accumulated  influence  of  past  generations 
over  the  present.  The  human  beings  themselves,  on 
the  laws  of  whose  nature  the  facts  of  history  depend,  are 
not  abstract  or  universal,  but  historical  human  beings, 
already  shaped,  and  made  what  they  are,  by  human 
society."  3 

But  these  two  modes  of  approach  to  social  science,  the 
psychological  and  the  historical,  the  deductive  and  the 
observational,  are  not  contradictory,  but  are  complementary 
elements  in  one  whole.  Reasoning  without  verification  by 
facts,  or  collections  of  facts  without  reference  to  law,  are 
alike  worthless.  A  right  scientific  method  recognizes  that 
either  element  implies  the  other;  the  order  in  which  they  are 
to  be  taken,  whether  the  verification  be  experience  or  reason 
ing,  whether  the  conclusion  be  logically  deduced  or  pro 
visionally  derived  from  experience,  makes  no  essential  dif 
ference  so  long  as  their  relations  are  kept  clear,  but  depends 
on  the  degree  of  complexity  in  the  particular  subject  studied. 
There  can  be  a  direct  deduction  of  tendencies,  if  not  of  facts, 
so  that  social  science  need  not  in  all  cases  be  looked  upon,  as 
by  Comte,  as  "essentially  consisting  of  generalizations  from 

1  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  63. 

2  Logic,  Bk.  VI,  Ch.  VII,  §  5;  8th  edition,  p.  613. 

3  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  84. 


84  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

history,   verified,   not  originally  suggested,   by  deductions 
from  the  laws  of  human  nature."  1 

When  we  pass  from  metaphysical  and  methodological  con 
siderations  to  the  problems  of  human  life  in  their  application 
to  individual  and  social  conduct,  Comte  represents  a  reaction 
against  the  views  which  Mill  developed;  he  revolts  against 
the  past  of  which  Mill  is  the  fulfillment.  Comte  denounces 
Rousseau  for  finding  reality  only  in  the  individual,  idealizing 
the  natural  man  in  isolation  from  society,  and  goes  to  the  op 
posite  extreme  in  the  declaration  that  "the  true  human  point 
of  view  is  not  individual  but  social.  .  .  .  Man  is  a  mere  ab 
straction,  and  there  is  nothing  real  but  humanity;"  2  whereas 
Mill,  though  he  corrects  Bentham's  over-emphasis  of  self- 
interest,  which  unwarrantably  restricts  man's  impulses 
solely  to  those  referring  to  self,  by  admitting  the  elementary 
and  inescapable  character  of  social  relations,  yet  he  does  this 
by  way  of  the  needed  supplementation  of  a  half-truth  in 
stead  of  by  a  complete  rejection  of  it,  and  still  lays  stronger 
emphasis  on  the  individual  than  on  society  as  an  entity. 
It  is  equally  true  that  the  individual  cannot  exist  as  an  in 
dividual  apart  from  society,  by  which  he  is  defined,  and  that 
society  is  real  only  by  means  of  its  component  individuals. 
Comte  denied  this  last  in  his  conception  of  humanity  as  a 
being  in  a  sense  external  to  individual  men,  real  in  a  meaning 
deeper  than  their  reality. 

But  Mill  does  not  go  all  the  way  to  the  counter  extreme. 
While  primarily  insisting  on  the  relations  of  individuals  in 
partial  independence  of  each  other,  he  does  not  ignore  that 
aspect  of  the  truth  which  lays  stress  on  the  incompleteness 
of  that  independence.  He  accepts,  albeit  with  qualifications, 
the  organic  view  of  society  set  forth  by  Comte.  According 
to  this  view  the  race  is  a  single,  evolving  unity  of  self- 
development,  of  which  individuals  are  members  or  organs, 
having  no  function  apart  from  the  furtherance  of  the  race. 
Temporally  this  race-life  is  one,  a  continuous,  unified  process, 

1  Logic,  Bk.  VI,  Ch.  IX,  §  i;  8th  edition,  p.  621. 

2  Auguste  Comte,  Philosophic  positive,  Vol.  VI,  p.  692;  tr.  by  Harriet 
Martineau,  Vol.  II,  p.  508. 


MILL  AND  COMTE  85 

because  the  present  is  inseparable  from  the  past,  is  modified 
by  all  the  cumulative  reactions  which  have  preceded  it,  so 
that  "the  living  are  always  more  and  more  dominated  by  the 
dead." 

Since  progress  is  thus  regarded,  not  as  a  web,  but  as  a  single 
thread  whose  strands  cannot  be  separated,  every  attempt  to 
treat  certain  relations  to  the  exclusion  of  others  involves  an 
abstraction  from  which  we  must  return  to  that  unity  of 
reality  in  which  all  influences  modify  and  interpenetrate 
each  other,  if  we  are  to  know  the  truth.  Now  while  Mill  is 
ready  to  acknowledge  the  interaction  of  the  various  phases 
of  the  social  order,  he  is  awake  to  the  practical  difficulties  of 
a  procedure  which  demands  that  we  attend  to  everything 
at  once.  Mill  contends  that  the  separation  of  the  depart 
ments  of  social  inquiry  is  not  a  matter  of  wilful  abstraction 
from  what  may  be  studied  as  a  single  whole.  For  progress 
is  not  unilinear.  Certain  aspects  develop  at  a  more  rapid 
rate  than  others,  and  moreover  the  interdependence  is  not 
perfect  but  is  more  intimate  between  some  parts  than  others. 
Different  species  of  fact  depend  on  different  kinds  of  causes 
and  therefore  must  be  studied  by  themselves  as  "  distinct 
and  separate,  though  not  independent,  branches  or  depart 
ments  of  sociological  speculation."  1  Conditions  may  be 
further  isolated  even  in  a  given  special  department,  by 
treating  as  constant  those  which  change  most  slowly  and 
considering  the  law  of  variations  with  reference  only  to  those 
selected  conditions  which  remain.  This  modification  of  the 
organic  view  of  society  substitutes  for  Comte's  unbifurcating 
broad  highway  a  pluralistic  conception  of  paths  which  meet 
and  interlace  and  separate  again  on  the  plain  of  social 
reality. 

Mill  is  therefore  prepared  to  consider  the  relations  of  the 
parts  to  one  another,  rather  than  to  regard  the  parts  as 
altogether  subservient  to  the  simple  and  perfect  whole,  when 
the  question  is  one  of  the  authority  of  society  over  the  free 
dom  of  individual  development,  as  well  as  when  it  is  one  of 
right  to  existence  of  sciences  which  apply  to  only  partial 
1  Logic,  Bk.  VI,  Ch.  IX,  §  3;  8th  edition,  p.  623. 


86  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

aspects  of  social  life.    This  opposition  in  their  views  of  the 

connection  between  whole  and  part,  humanity  and  men,  is 

|  represented  by  Mill's  passionate  protest  against,  and  Comte's 

I  allegiance  to,  the  unlimited  power  of  the  government,  the 

'  practical  authority  of  men  over  women,  and  the  restriction 

of  intellectual  freedom  in  investigation  and  speech;  that  is, 

in  the  formation  and  expression  of  opinion,  and  of  practical 

freedom  in  putting  those  opinions  into  effect.     In  all  these 

points  it  is  the  total  static  outcome  which  Comte  holds  of 

value,  not  the  highest  possible  attainment  through  effort,  by 

which  the  largest  number  of  individuals   is   progressively 

realized.     For  him  the  independence  of  thought  and  action 

is  not  essential  to  healthy  growth,  but  a  mere  destructive 

and  negative  revolt  against  the  supreme  authority  which 

holds  the  keys  of  truth  and  morality. 

This  authority,  so  far  as  conduct  is  concerned,  is  central 
ized  by  Comte  entirely  in  the  government.  Social  reform 
cannot  aim  at  general  reconstruction;  it  can  do  no  more  than 
restore  the  spirit  of  willing  subordination  on  the  part  of  the 
masses  to  leaders  inspired  by  the  sense  of  social  duty.  The 
working  of  the  system  may  need  reformation,  but  not  the 
structure  of  the  system  itself.  Democracy  means  no  more 
to  him  than  the  rule  of  the  superior  by  the  inferior.  How 
can  the  inferiors,  the  common  people,  be  capable  of  distin 
guishing  as  rulers,  their  superiors?  Ultimate  power  is  in 
such  a  case  vested  in  the  hands  of  those  least  fitted  to  wield 
it;  the  weak  are  made  judges  of  the  strong.  The  mode  of 
selecting  officials,  according  to  Comte's  scheme,  should  be 
appointment  by  their  predecessors  in  office,  subject  to  the 
approval,  not  of  their  inferiors,  the  common  people,  but  of 
their  official  superiors.  Moreover,  the  idea  of  equality  is 
only  another  obstacle  to  efficiency.  If  society  is  an  organism, 
it  can  run  smoothly  only  if  different  organs  have  different 
functions.  This  may  be  true,  but  it  makes  a  great  deal  of 
difference  whether,  from  a  basis  of  initial  equality  as  perfect 
as  possible,  that  is,  equality  of  the  external  conditions  and 
equality  of  opportunity,  individuals  freely  choose  what  or 
gans  they  will  be  and  what  functions  they  will  perform,  or 


MILL  AND  COMTE  87 

whether  certain  disqualifications  attend  some  of  them  from 
the  beginning. 

Mill's  positive  position  on  the  limitation  of  the  power  of 
government  over  the  individual,  his  insistence  on  natural 
equality  of  ability  and  the  essential  justice  of  the  laissez 
faire  doctrine,  has  been  considered.  His  difference  from 
Comte  in  these  respects  is  founded  on  a  difference  as  to  the 
whole  end  in  view,  the  entire  justification  of  life.  "It  is  not 
the  uncontrolled  ascendancy  of  popular  power  but  of  any 
power,  which  is  formidable."  *  The  object  is  not  accomplish 
ment  of  a  definite  purpose  by  humanity  at  large,  the  main 
tenance  of  a  state  devoid  of  friction,  in  which  the  inferior  are 
always  obedient  to  the  superior,  but  devoid  of  initiative. 
The  ideal  is  rather  a  voluntary  union  of  freely  active  in 
dividuals.  A  given  result  may  be  reached  by  circuitous 
routes,  by  doubling  back  and  blind  straying  from  the  path, 
by  mistakes  innumerable;  but  they  are  the  errors  of  men 
who  do  not  follow  in  darkness  the  light  of  leaders  with  whose 
direction  and  destination  they  have  no  concern,  but  of  men 
each  one  of  whom  bears  a  light  of  his  own,  be  it  but  a  glim 
mering  rushlight,  and  knows  where  his  feet  will  fall,  be  it 
for  only  a  few  steps  in  advance.  External  perfection  may  be 
attained  more  quickly  by  the  'benevolent  tyrant,'  but  it 
will  not  be  so  well  worth  attaining.  If  society  progresses  at 
the  expense  of  the  individual,  it  will  be  "dead  perfection,  no 
more,"  devoid  of  the  spirit  of  adventure,  of  the  lure  of  un 
tried  possibilities,  the  glory  of  dangerous  mistakes,  the 
responsibility  which  the  lowest  member  of  it  may  share  and, 
by  so  sharing,  take  a  conscious  and  creative,  not  a  merely 
mechanical,  part  in  the  life  of  the  world. 

In  the  position  which  he  gave  to  women,  Mill  discerned  in 
Comte  an  instance  of  a  class  of  human  beings  isolated  ab 
initio  from  the  activities  of  the  community,  a  class  differen 
tiated  for  the  performance  of  certain  functions  and  debarred 
from  others,  regardless  of  individual  capacities.  Comte's 
attitude  towards  women  underwent  a  radical  change,  which, 
however,  did  not  affect  the  point  at  issue,  their  freedom  as 
1  Bain,  John  Stuart  Mill,  p.  80. 


88  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

individual  human  beings.  He  first  regarded  them  as  in  all 
respects  inferior  and  subordinate  to  men.  Later  his  opin 
ions  were  modified  without,  to  Mill's  mind,  becoming  more 
rational.  "Instead  of  being  treated  as  grown  children,  they 
were  exalted  as  goddesses:  honours,  privileges  and  immu 
nities  were  showered  upon  them,  only  not  simple  justice."  1 
They  were  to  take  no  part  in  public  affairs,  to  be  allowed  no 
self-expression  or  economic  independence  by  means  of  an 
occupation,  but  were  to  serve  as  the  guardian  angels  of  the 
men, — a  mission  for  which  by  no  means  all  women,  by  virtue 
merely  of  being  women,  are  peculiarly  fitted.  Of  Comte's 
two  points  of  view,  the  first  is  probably  the  less  galling.  It 
has  at  least  the  advantage  of  straightforward  sincerity.  The 
second  cages  woman  just  as  effectively  away  from  her  place 
as  man's  comrade  in  the  world's  activity,  under  the  pretence 
of  honoring  her.  The  pedestal  is  not  an  acceptable  sub 
stitute  for  room  in  which  to  work.  Whether,  when  the 
obscurities  of  sex  psychology  are  brought  to  light  and  clearly 
formulated,  Mill's  contention  of  equality  of  the  sexes  be 
justified  or  no,  he  at  any  rate  follows  the  path  which  the 
modern  movements  are  taking. 

Mill  opposes  what  he  conceives  to  be  the  tyranny  of  the 
mass  over  the  individual,  which  Comte  upholds,  whether  it 
be  in  terms  of  class  or  of  sex.  The  laissezfaire  principle  holds  - 
even  in  the  latter  case,  where  special  legislation  has  been 
most  demanded.  "  Women  are  as  capable  as  men  ...  of 
managing  their  own  concerns,  and  the  only  hindrance  to 
their  doing  so  arises  from  the  injustice  of  their  present  social 
position."  :  A  woman's  right  over  her  own  person  and  prop 
erty  should  not  be  interfered  with  by  such  legislation  as  that 
on  factory  labor,  which  ignores  the  fact  that  women  in  fac 
tories  are  the  only  women  of  the  laboring  classes  who  are  not 
bound  down  by  oppressive  laws  which  make  them  slaves  and 
drudges  to  their  husbands.  Even  in  the  marriage  contract, 
which  Comte  views  as  inviolable,  no  iron-bound  law  should 
compel  people  to  follow  a  course  of  conduct  which  may  in 

1  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  92. 

2  Political  Economy,  Bk.  V,  Ch.  XI,  §  9. 


MILL  AND  COMTE  89 

the  concrete  case  be  inexpedient  or  definitely  harmful. 
Marriage  is  a  contract  which  should  be  revocable.  So  only 
can  voluntary  co-operation,  the  free  choice  of  the  individual, 
supplant  mechanical  obedience  to  a  decree  imposed  from 
without. 

The  principle  of  equality,  which  is  bound  up  with  that  of 
laissez  faire,  leads  Mill  to  consider  difference  in  sex  alto 
gether  irrelevant  to  the  freedom  to  exercise  political  rights  or 
to  choose  the  occupations  by  which  economic  independence 
may  be  established.  "All  human  beings  have  the  same  in 
terest  in  good  government;  the  welfare  of  all  is  alike  affected 
by  it,  and  they  have  equal  need  of  a  voice  in  it  to  secure  their 
share  of  its  benefits."  1  The  main  point  is  that  of  individual 
freedom.  Society  cannot  decide  for  the  individual  woman, 
any  more  than  for  the  individual  man,  what  she  is  fit  to 
attempt.  The  only  thing  to  do  is  to  try  it  out,  by  the  aboli 
tion  of  all  exclusions  and  disabilities  which  close  any  honest 
employment  to  anyone.  If  such  a  course  entails  a  decrease 
in  general  efficiency  until  the  slow  process  of  natural  adjust 
ment  has  set  things  straight,  the  disadvantage  is  not  equal 
to  the  deadening  influence  of  an  a  priori  decision  in  the 
appointment  of  tasks.  "The  same  reasons  which  make  it 
no  longer  necessary  that  the  poor  should  depend  on  the  rich, 
make  it  equally  unnecessary  that  women  should  depend  on 
men.  .  .  .  The  ideas  and  institutions  by  which  the  accident 
of  sex  is  made  the  groundwork  of  an  inequality  of  legal  rights 
and  a  forced  dissimilarity  of  social  functions,  must  ere  long 
be  recognized  as  the  greatest  hindrance  to  moral,  social,  and 
even  intellectual  improvement."  2 

These  dissimilar  views  of  the  civic  and  political  relation 
between  authority  and  individual  activity  are  further  carried 
out  in  the  realm  of  thought,  both  in  theory  and  as  exemplified 
in  practice.  For  Comte  t,he  right  of  private  judgment  is  a 
rebellious  emancipation  from  spiritual  authority.  The  whole 
course  of  education  is  to  stifle  questions  and  to  accept  every 
thing  on  the  unchallenged  authority  of  the  teachers.  It  is 

1  Representative  Government,  p.  29. 

2  Political  Economy,  Bk.  IV,  Ch.  VII,  §  3. 


90  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

again  the  emphasis  on  the  result  instead  of  the  process;  the 
aim  is  to  hand  on  certain  established  facts,  not  to  teach  the 
student  how  to  think  for  himself  so  that  he  may  learn  how 
to  test  the  claimants  for  acceptance  as  truth.  No  proofs, 
therefore,  need  be  given;  for  an  over-anxiety  for  proof  breaks 
down  existing  knowledge.  Comte  ignores  the  consideration 
that  existing  knowledge  which  can  be  broken  down  by  the 
zeal  for  proof  is  not  genuine  knowledge  at  all.  On  the  con 
trary,  he  condemns  revolt  against  tradition  as  in  itself  bad. 
Thus  the  statement  that  the  living  are  always  more  and  more 
dominated  by  the  dead  is  re-interpreted  to  mean  that  we 
should  submit  to  the  authority  of  the  past,  not  doubt  its 
judgment  nor  test  by  our  own  reason  or  discoveries  the 
grounds  of  its  opinions. 

In  this  moral  and  intellectual  authority  whose  judgments 
are  to  be  unquestioned  Mill  sees  one  of  those  half-truths 
which  constitute  the  worst  error.  It  is  indeed  incontrovert 
ible  that  most  opinions  are  received  on  the  authority  of 
experts  who  have  devoted  time,  labor,  and  exceptional 
ability  to  their  working  out.  Such  a  division  of  labor  is 
essential,  since  no  man  can  be  a  compendium  of  universal 
knowledge,  and  it  involves  faith  in  the  conclusions  of  men 
whose  work  cannot  be  examined  in  detail  by  the  layman*. 

iBut  the  danger  lies  in  vesting  this  leadership  with  a'n  au 
thority  other  than  the  place  which  it  wins  by  its  own  merit. 
An  "organized  body''  whose  edicts  are  above  question 
"would  involve  nothing  less  than  a  spiritual  despotism," 
worse  even  than  a  temporal  despotism,  as  the  force  of  an 
irresistible  public  opinion"  is  more  subtly  penetrative 
than  the  force  of  government.1  The  people  "should  feel 
respect  for  superiority  of  intellect  and  knowledge,  and  defer 
much  to  the  opinions  on  any  subject  of  those  whom  they 
think  well  acquainted  with  it."  But  the  allegiance  is  freely 
given,  not  demanded.  "They  will  judge  for  themselves  of 
the  persons  who  are  and  are  not  entitled  to  it."  2 

This  liberty  in  the  formation  of  opinions  carries  with  it 

1  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  98. 

2  Political  Economy,  Bk.  IV,  Ch.  VII,  §  2. 


MILL  AND  COMTE  91 

freedom  of  expression.  No  authorized  body  can  be  the  in 
fallible  teacher  who  can  say,  This  shalt  thou  think,  and  This 
shalt  thou  speak,  and  to  doubt  whom  is  heresy.  "The  no 
tion  .  .  .  that  a  government  should  choose  opinions  for  the 
people,  and  should  not  suffer  any  doctrines  in  politics, 
morals,  law,  or  religion,  but  such  as  it  approves,  to  be  printed 
or  publicly  professed,  may  be  said  to  be  altogether  aban 
doned  as  a  general  thesis.  .  .  .  The  human  mind,  when 
prevented  either  by  fear  of  the  law  or  by  fear  of  opinion 
from  exercising  its  faculties  freely  on  the  most  important 
subjects,  acquires  a  general  torpidity  and  imbecility,  by 
which,  when  they  reach  a  certain  point,  it  is  disqualified 
from  making  any  considerable  advances  even  in  the  com 
mon  affairs  of  life,  and  which,  when  greater  still,  make 
it  gradually  lose  even  its  previous  attainments."  1  Here 
again  the  vital  thing  for  Mill  is  not  the  acceptance  of  an  ex 
ternally  complete  and  inviolable  set  of  truths,  but  the  realiza 
tion  of  the  powers  of  each  mind  affected  by  those  truths. 

Moreover,  in  his  essay  On  Liberty  he  maintains  that  truth 
is  not  established  by  the  suppression  of  controversy  but  is 
brought  clearly  to  light  only  by  the  recognition  of  what  may 
be  said  against  it.  Only  so,  and  not  by  unchallenged  re 
iteration  can  the  meaning  be  constantly  renewed  and  kept 
vivid  in  the  minds  of  its  supporters  as  in  the  minds  of  those 
who  first  had  to  fight  for  its  acceptance.  If  the  opinion  in 
question  is  error  mistaken  for  truth,  its  error  can  obviously 
be  made  plain  only  if  freedom  of  attack  be  permitted.  But 
for  Comte  there  are  no  such  contested  points.  He  assumes 
that  the  class  set  apart  as  investigators  will  do  nothing 
which  needs  to  be  revised  or  reversed  by  the  discoveries  of 
a  succeeding  generation. 

As  to  the  realization  of  thought  in  action,  Comte  again 
prefers  a  blind  right  course  to  an  intelligent  mistake.  The 
entire  responsibility  for  conduct  devolves  on  the  aristocratic 
caste  set  apart  for  the  purpose.  "Liberty  and  spontaneity 
on  the  part  of  individuals  form  no  part  of  the  scheme."  2 

1  Political  Economy,  Bk.  V,  Ch.  X,  §  6. 

-  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  123. 


92 


PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 


And  with  that  liberty  and  spontaneity  is  taken  away  the 
freedom  of  choice  which  takes  its  chance  of  error  and  hews 
out  the  form  of  the  moral  character  of  a  man.  "Every 
particle  of  conduct,  public  or  private,  is  to  be  open  to  the 
public  eye,  and  to  be  kept,  by  the  power  of  opinion,  in  the 
course  which  the  spiritual  corporation  shall  judge  to  be  the 
most  right."  Against  this  Mill  sets  his  doctrine  that,  "as  a 
rule  of  conduct,  to  be  enforced  by  moral  sanctions,  we  think 
no  more  should  be  attempted  than  to  prevent  people  from 
doing  harm  to  others,  or  omitting  to  do  such  good  as  they 
have  undertaken."  1  The  difficulty  of  drawing  the  line,  of 
measuring  the  extent  of  man's  partial  independence  and  his 
connection  with  the  social  whole,  so  that  application  can 
b-  made  of  the  formula,  "The  individual  is  not  accountable 
to  society  for  his  actions,  in  so  far  as  these  concern  the  in 
terests  of  no  person  but  himself,"  belongs  to  Mill's  social 
theory  as  a  whole.  Since  for  him  society  is  not  the  end  in 
itself,  but  the  condition  for  the  development  of  individual 
character,  the  freedom  to  work  out  one's  will  in  the  external 
world,  the  carrying  of  freedom  of  thought  to  its  natural 
outcome  in  life,  must  be  preserved  as  far  as  possible  to  each 
individual. 

The  ideas  on  which  these  two  conceptions  of  the  relative 
value  of  freedom  and  obedience  to  authority  are  based  re 
duce  to  a  difference  of  ethical  ideals  and  methods.  Is  the 
highest  good  the  minimum  of  discord  and  friction  with  the 
maximum  of  efficiency  in  the  general  progress  of  humanity, 
or  is  it  the  development  of  the  largest  possible  number  of 
persons  into  autonomous  personalities  which  include,  but 
are  not  entirely  absorbed  by,  the  relation  to  others  which 
binds  them  together  into  a  society?  As  Comte  endorses 
the  first  ideal,  he  maintains  not  merely  that  the  line  be 
tween  self-regarding  and  other-regarding  acts  is  hard  to 
draw,  but  that  there  should,  as  nearly  as  possible,  be  no 
self-regarding  acts  at  all.  He  is  as  one-sidedly  social  as 
Bentham  is  one-sidedly  egoistic.  Self-interest,  so  far  from 
being  the  ultimate  motive  for  all  conduct,  must,  in  his  view^ 
1  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  145. 


MILL  AND  COMTE  93 

though  originally  strong,  be  conquered  and  superseded  by 
an  exclusive  attention  to  the  good  of  others  as  the  only  in 
ducement  on  which  we  should  allow  ourselves  to  act.  Al 
truism  is  not  merely  the  most  important  moral  motive  but 
the  only  one.  Personal  satisfaction  should  be  starved  to  the 
last  degree  in  the  endeavor  not  to  love  ourselves  at  all. 
Comte,  says  Mill,  adapting  Novalis's  characterization  of 
Spinoza,  was  a  morality-intoxicated  man.1  Mill's  own  view 
is  in  a  sense  a  synthesis  of  the  two  opposing  ethical  theories : 
the  egoistic  hedonism  of  Bentham  and  the  equally  one 
sided  altruism  of  Comte.  He  does,  it  is  true,  set  the  egoistic 
and  altruistic  impulses  over  against  one  another  as  conflict 
ing,  not  as  involving  each  other.  My  self-regarding  and 
other-regarding  acts  can  be  tabulated, — a  proceeding  ex 
ceedingly  difficult  in  practice.  But  he  also  maintains  a 
relation  between  them  other  than  that  of  mutual  negation; 
he  holds  that  a  reasonable  gratification  of  the  egoistic  feel 
ings  is  favorable  to  the  growth  of  benevolent  affections. 
"The  moralization  of  the  personal  enjoyments  we  deem  to 
consist,  not  in  reducing  them  to  the  smallest  possible  amount, 
but  in  cultivating  the  habitual  wish  to  share  them  with 
others,  and  with  all  others,  and  scorning  to  desire  anything 
for  oneself  which  is  incapable  of  being  so  shared." 

Comte's  insistence  that  morality  can  include  only  one 
set  of  motives  with  which  all  others  are  in  eternal  conflict 
is  an  example  of  the  passion  for  unity  which  results  in  an 
over-simplification  and  over-systematization  of  life  and 
conduct.  Mill  has  always  an  eye  for  the  concrete  complexi 
ties,  the  infinite  variety  in  experience,  which,  in  its  joyous 
recognition  of  differences  and  refusal  to  throw  them  all  into 
one  pot  and  make  them  one  by  the  crude  process  of  melt 
ing,  makes  pluralism  immediately  appeal  to  our  sense  of 
the  genuine  intricacy  of  reality.  Why,  asks  Mill,  must  man 
care  for  only  one  thing,  not  self  and  others?  Why  is  it 
necessary  that  all  human  life  should  point  to  but  one  ob 
ject,  and  be  cultivated  into  a  system  of  means  to  a  single 
end?  When  thus  thrown  into  relief  against  Comte's  ex- 

1  Auguste  Comte  and  Positivism,  p.  145.  2  Ibid.,  p.  141. 


94  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

treme  socialism  and  monism,  Mill's  individualism  and 
pluralism  do  not  take  an  extreme  and  abstract  form,  but 
appear  as  the  effort  to  achieve  a  synthesis  between  the 
spirit  of  Bentham  on  the  one  hand  and  that  of  Comte  on 
the  other.  The  attempt  to  assimilate  the  best  of  the  new 
into  the  development  of  the  old  may  not  always  be  perfectly 
successful,  but  the  impression  left  is  of  one  who  came  nearer 
to  the  truth  of  our  social  and  moral  experience  than  did 
either  of  the  upholders  of  the  opposing  positions. 


THE    INTELLECTUALISTIC   VOLUNTARISM   OF 
ALFRED  FOUILLEE 

ALMA  THORNE  PENNEY 

IN    the    philosophy    of   Alfred    Fouillee    the    two    main 
currents   of  nineteenth   century   thought    are   brought   to 
gether   to   form   a    comprehensive   whole.     The    synthetic 
character  of  his  work  remains  the  same  from  the  earliest 
inception  of  the  doctrine  of  idee-force  to  the  posthumous 
Esquisse  d'une  interpretation  du  monde,  which  he  was  pre 
paring  for  publication  when  he  was  overcome  by  his  last 
illness  in  the  summer  of  1912.     For  more  than  forty  years, 
during   which   time   thirty-four   books   appeared   from   his 
prolific   pen,    Fouillee    devoted    himself    to    the    consistent 
presentation  of  a  system  developed  from  the  conception  of 
intellect  and  will  as  fundamentally  one.     In  his  later  works 
he  called  this  philosophy  an  intellectualistic  voluntarism. 
No  better  term  could  be  used  to  describe  it.     It  is  not  an 
eclecticism,  such  as  the  work  of  Victor  Cousin,  nor  is  it  a 
dualism  of  Will  and  Idea,  such  as  Schopenhauer's.     It  is  a 
monistic  system  involving  a  synthesis  of  naturalism  and 
idealism  by  means  of  psychical  factors  common  to  both. 
In  this  synthesis,  the  underlying  principle  of  which  is  idee- 
force,  causality  is  shown  to  be  psychical  and  ideas  are  shown 
to  be  not  only  facts  of  consciousness  but  forces.    Reality  is 
will,  but  it  is  not  merely  will.     It  is  impossible  to  speak  of 
will  as  a  thing  apart.    Will  is  indissolubly  joined  with  intel 
ligence,  and  it  is  in  the  'conscious  subject'  that  Fouillee 
finds  the  only  original  and  sure  manifestation  of  the  Real, 
existing  in  itself  and  for  itself.     The  essence  of  his  whole 
philosophy  is  crowded  into  the  phrase  with  which  he  even 
tually  characterized  this  conception  of  reality:  la  volonte 
de  conscience. 

Voluntarism  is  no  new  philosophy  in  France.     Founded 


96  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

by  Maine  de  Biran,  who  died  in  1824,  the  voluntaristic 
school  of  thought  has  gathered  to  itself  a  long  line  of  dis 
ciples,  including  writers  of  such  widely  differing  opinions 
as  Renouvier,  Ravaisson,  Boutroux,  Bergson,  Le  Roy,  and 
Wilbois.  Fouillee  is  allied  with  none  of  these,  save  in  regard 
to  a  few  scattered  details  of  doctrine,  because  Fouillee  con 
sistently  emphasizes  the  oneness  of  mental  life  and  refuses 
to  erect  a  metaphysic  upon  a  partial  view  of  reality.  Volun 
tarism  by  itself  seems  to  him  as  one-sided  as  the  old  ra 
tionalism  which  it  opposes.  From  Maine  de  Biran  to  Berg- 
son,  voluntarists  have  neglected  the  part  played  by  the 
understanding.  In  the  philosophy  of  Bergson  this  neglect 
is  more  than  a  mere  omission.  It  is  a  militant  anti-intellec- 
tualism.  All  of  these  thinkers,  however,  agree  in  regarding 
volitional  activity  as  fundamental  to  reality  and  to  a  theory 
of  knowledge.  All  of  them  lay  more  or  less  emphasis  upon 
the  psychological  fact  of  the  immediate  consciousness  of 
personal  activity.  The  dynamic  character  of  reality  re 
ceives  different  names  according  to  the  divergent  concep 
tions  of  these  voluntarists.  Maine  de  Biran  calls  it  spiritual 
istic  activism;  Ravaisson  calls  it  liberty;  Boutroux  pleads 
for  contingency  in  the  laws  of  nature;  Fouillee  conceives  of 
it  as  volonte  de  conscience,  a  continuous  elan  en  avant,  a  never 
ceasing  evolution  novatrice;  Bergson,  in  strikingly  similar 
language,  describes  reality  as  change,  an  elan  vital  accom 
plishing  a  perpetual  evolution  creatrice. 

In  all  of  these  conceptions  there  is  involved  a  rejection  of 
mechanistic  materialism.  From  the  time  of  Descartes  the 
French  mind  has  delighted  in  the  clearness  and  distinctness, 
the  neat  exactness,  and  the  perfect  rationality  of  mechanical 
science.  The  Cartesian  dualism  of  mind  and  matter  afforded 
a  starting  point  for  the  materialistic  movement  of  the  eight 
eenth  century.  If  Descartes  could  explain  a  dog  by  means 
of  mechanical  laws,  why  should  not  La  Mettrie  explain  man 
in  the  same  way?  Why  delve  into  the  mysteries  of  soul, 
when  the  brain  could  be  dissected  to  demonstrate  the  non- 
mysterious  character  of  mind?  Matter  and  motion  being 
the  ultimate  explanation  of  everything,  thought  is  best 


FOUILLEE'S  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  97 

employed  in  discovering  the  laws  of  a  mechanical  universe. 
In  this  field  the  metaphysical  aspect  of  materialism  was 
represented  by  Holbach's  Systeme  de  la  nature,  but  its  great 
est  achievements  were  within  the  realm  of  exact  science. 
In  the  discoveries  of  La  Grange  and  La  Place,  the  keenness 
of  the  French  intellect  is  demonstrated.  In  the  field  of 
natural  science  men  like  Lavoisier,  Berthollet,  Pasteur, 
Ampere,  Cuvier,  and  Lamarck  were  known  as  widely  as  the 
subjects  they  investigated.  It  was  an  age  of  empirical  in 
vestigation.  The  orderly  processes  of  scientific  method 
appealed  to  the  tidy  mind  of  the  French  thinker.  Small 
wonder  that  Comte  found  here  the  ideal  for  his  Positivism. 
Nor  is  it  to  be  wondered  at  that  out  of  this  empirical  era 
there  should  grow  a  new  philosophy,  at  once  constructive 
and  sceptical.  Littre,  Taine,  and  Renan  are  but  three  rep 
resentatives  of  this  school  of  thought,  and  its  influence  has 
been  very  far-reaching.  One  of  its  notable  results  has  been 
an  increased  interest  in  psychological  investigation,  though 
Comte's  Positivism  vehemently  denied  the  right  of  psychol 
ogy  to  exist.  From  Taine's  work,  De  V intelligence,  we  may 
trace  the  beginnings  of  several  lines  of  thought,  some  of 
which  have  resulted  in  a  reaction  against  science  itself,  as  a 
construction  of  the  intellect.  It  is  due  to  this  supposed  over 
emphasis  of  intellectual  elements  in  science  and  philosophy 
that  voluntaristic  philosophy  has  arisen  to  plead  the  cause 
of  the  volitional  elements.  Modern  French  thinkers  and 
writers  in  every  field  show  a  widespread  revolt  against  that 
"nightmare"  conception  of  the  universe  which  seeks  the 
progress  of  science  in  "the  gradual  banishment  from  all 
regions  of  human  thought  of  what  we  call  spirit  and  spon 
taneity."  l 

Materialism,  positivism,  intellectualism,  and  voluntarism 
alike  fail  to  satisfy  the  requirements  of  a  complete  philos 
ophy.  No  amount  of  scientific  method,  and  no  amount  of 
unscientific  intuitionism,  can  save  a  doctrine  from  the  charge 
of  superficiality,  if  it  is  based  upon  a  partial  or  one-sided  view 
of  reality.  This  sort  of  superficiality  is  not  to  be  confused 
1  Huxley,  Collected  Essays,  Vol.  I,  p.  159. 


98  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

with  the  sort  that  results  from  inadequate  language.  Pro 
found  doctrines  are  quite  able  to  be  expressed  in  simple 
language;  and  we  all  know  how  much  shallowness  of  thought 
may  be  concealed  by  the  ponderous  obscurity  of  an  uncouth 
terminology.  In  the  case  of  the  French  doctrines  in  ques 
tion  here,  there  is  no  obscurity.  Their  inadequacy  is  mainly 
due  to  their  failure  to  take  account  of  the  whole  of  reality. 
To  separate  matter  and  mind  for  purposes  of  discussion  is 
justifiable;  to  divide  the  mind  up  into  compartments  of 
intellect  and  feeling  and  will  may  be  equally  justifiable;  but 
to  build  a  world-view  upon  any  one  of  these  fragments  is 
to  construct  a  superficial  and  unsatisfactory  metaphysic. 
It  is  axiomatic  that  the  whole  is  greater  than  the  part,  and 
it  follows  that  any  attempt  to  promote  a  fragmentary  con 
ception  of  reality  to  the  dignity  of  the  whole  is  foredoomed 
to  failure.  It  was  this  aspect  of  earlier  French  philosophy 
that  Royce  had  in  mind,  when  he  compared  it  to  "a  rel 
atively  bare  room,  full  of  electric  lights,  that  shine  with 
brilliancy  upon  a  few  diagrams,  which  pretend  to  be  a  pic 
ture  of  the  universe."  l  It  is  this  aspect  also  that  engages 
the  attention  of  Fouillee  and  leads  him  to  attempt  a  syn 
thesis  which  shall  be  comprehensive  enough  to  include  the 
truth  of  all  these  divergent  systems. 

The  synthetic  character  of  Fouillee's  philosophy  was  estab 
lished  in  his  doctoral  thesis  on  La  liberte  et  le  determinisme 
in  1872,  but  it  reached  its  most  definite  expression  in  1879, 
when  he  published  in  the  Revue  philosophique  an  article  en 
titled,  "La  philosophic  des  idees-forces  comme  conciliation 
du  naturalisme  et  de  Pidealisme."  In  this  article  he  out 
lined  for  the  first  time  that  "methode  de  conciliation"  which 
he  applied  to  all  of  his  subsequent  work,  both  historical  and 
constructive.  The  chief  feature  of  this  method  was  the  use 
of  mean  terms  to  reconcile  differences  between  philosophical 
theories.  The  intercalation  of  such  a  series  of  mean  terms 
reduces  the  opposition  of  contraries  to  an  infinitesimal  dif 
ference.  Fouillee  was  indebted  to  Leibniz  for  the  suggestion 
that  differences  may  be  so  reduced  as  to  be  negligibly  small. 
1  "Jean  Marie  Guyau,"  Studies  of  Good  and  Evil,  p.  360. 


FOUILLEE'S  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  99 

Though  such  an  intercalation  of  mean  terms  may  not  result 
in  a  complete  identification  of  opposites,  it  does  result  in 
their  progressive  approximation  toward  unity.  It  succeeds 
in  introducing  harmony  where  there  was  discord,  and  con 
vergence  where  there  was  divergence. 

The  first  application  of  this  method  had  appeared  in  La 
liberte  et  la  determinisme ,  in  which  Fouillee  had  advanced 
the  theory  that  the  idea  of  freedom  serves  as  an  intermediary 
between  freedom  and  determinism.  The  force  of  the  thought 
itself  is  such  that  it  is  bound  to  arouse  a  striving  and  to 
generate  power.  Scientific  determinism  then  loses  its  hold 
on  moral  activity.  Moral  freedom  becomes  progressively 
more  assured  as  we  strive  more  and  more  to  conceive  our 
auto-determinism.  In  an  unpublished  fragment  the  idea 
of  freedom  is  defined  as  "the  self  having  consciousness  of  its 
own  power  in  its  tendency  to  break  down  all  barriers  and 
surmount  all  obstacles."  It  is  the  self  at  once  conceiving 
and  desiring  its  own  independence.  This  idea  of  individual 
causality  is  the  first  stage  of  freedom;  but  the  second  stage, 
in  which  alone  freedom  is  complete,  is  dominated  by  the 
idea  of  universal  finality.  The  first  stage  posits  the  self; 
the  second  stage  unites  the  self  to  the  whole.  The  passage 
from  one  stage  to  the  other  is  assured  by  the  psychological 
origin  of  the  consciousness  of  self-activity.  There  is  always 
a  non-self  acting  on  the  self,  and  the  self  is  always  reacting 
on  the  milieu  which  limits  it.  In  this  way  there  arises  a 
recognition  of  the  obstacle  as  another  will,  then  a  recognition 
of  a  plurality  of  wills.  The  subject  thus  objectifies  itself  and 
passes  from  the  conception  of  another  will  to  the  conception 
of  a  universality  of  causes  and  effects.  The  will  is  a  "per 
petual  marche  en  avant"  or  a  perpetual  induction.  "It  is 
possible  for  it  to  expand  toward  the  universal  because  it  is 
a  force,  and  that  expansive  power  is  the  very  essence  of 
force."  * 

The  method  here  outlined  was  amplified  greatly  in  the 
statement  given  it  in  1879.  The  distinct  steps  to  be  taken 
were  clearly  described  and  the  application  of  the  method  to 
1  La  liberte  et  le  determinisme,  p.  274. 


100  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  history  of  philosophy  pointed  out.  As  a  matter  of  fact, 
Fouillee  had  already  employed  the  method  in  his  own  His- 
toire  generate  de  la  philosophie,  which  appeared  in  1875.  In 
reconciling  opposing  philosophies  the  historian  should  con 
struct  as  well  as  criticise.  He  should  carry  out  principles  to 
their  consequences  and  realize  the  ideal  of  the  doctrines  he 
interprets.  "It  is  better  to  complete  than  to  refute."  We 
cannot  complete  a  theory  until  we  comprehend  it,  and  to 
comprehend  a  philosopher  we  must  place  ourselves  at  his 
point  of  view  rather  than  our  own.  The  historian  of  philos 
ophy  must  enter  into  the  spirit  of  systems  and  interpret 
them  as  they  aspire  to  be  interpreted,  by  their  great  elements 
rather  than  by  their  imperfections.  True  appreciation  is  a 
complement  of  comprehension,  and  it  consists  in  two  main 
moments:  the  correction  of  errors  and  the  reconciliation  of 
truths.  Incomplete  theories  are  to  be  joined  to  each  other 
only  through  their  relation  to  the  complete  whole,  the  per 
fect  unity,  of  which  they  are  a  partial  expression.  The 
completion  of  philosophical  systems  by  means  of  absorp 
tion  in  others  is,  in  Fouillee's  opinion,  of  the  greatest  im 
portance  to  their  existence.  Progress  is  achieved  in  thought 
much  in  the  same  way  as  in  the  evolution  of  the  animal  king 
dom.  A  limit  of  development  having  been  reached,  dete 
rioration  follows,  unless  new  blood  be  added  by  selection. 
So,  too,  philosophical  systems  must  be  renewed  by  other 
systems,  in  order  to  preserve  their  vital  force.  The  method 
of  reconciliation  is  one  of  progress  from  the  good  that  is  old 
to  the  good  that  is  new.  All  that  is  merely  eclecticism  or 
syncretism  disappears,  till  only  the  true  synthesis  remains. 

From  the  foregoing  brief  statement  of  the  early  work  of 
Fouillee  it  will  appear  that  he  was  already  far  on  the  road 
of  synthetic  philosophizing  when  he  first  gave  the  name  of 
idee-force  to  the  principle  which  is  the  unifying  element  in 
his  constructive  synthesis  of  voluntarism  and  intellectualism. 
From  1879  till  his  death  in  1912  his  philosophy  was  known 
to  the  world  as  the  "philosophic  des  idees-forces." 

In  order  to  understand  what  is  connoted  by  these  thought- 
forces  it  is  necessary  to  know  their  genesis.  Fouillee  frankly 


FOUILLEE'S  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  IOI 

bases  his  doctrine  on  psychology.  His  point  of  departure  is 
that  of  the  'thinking  subject/  for  whom  reality  is  immanent 
in  his  own  consciousness.  Reality  can  be  reached  only 
through  experience,  and  principally  through  psychological 
reflection.  Consciousness  is  the  condition  of  all  experience. 
More  than  that,  it  is  the  primordial  experience  itself,  the 
irreducible  and  ultimately  real  Being.  Psychological  re 
flection,  then,  is  something  more  than  the  discovery  and 
enumeration  of  successive  states  of  consciousness.  When 
we  enter  into  ourselves  to  investigate  the  nature  of  this 
immanent  reality,  we  do  not  leap  into  a  void,  but  (the 
phrase  suggests  Bergson)  we  "plunge  into  the  real."  Psy 
chology  must  be  taken  as  the  basis  of  general  philosophy  be 
cause  it  is  the  study  of  the  indissoluble  union  of  thought  and 
will.  To  know  what  Being  is,  we  have  only  to  ask  ourselves 
with  what  fundamental  characteristics  it  is  felt,  known,  and 
willed.  This  seems  to  Fouillee  not  only  the  most  direct 
method  of  approaching  the  essential  problems  of  meta 
physics,  but  the  only  one  which  does  not  exclude  in  advance 
every  intelligible  solution.  We  cannot  put  ourselves  out 
side  of  the  universal  reality,  for  then  it  would  no  longer  be 
universal.  The  metaphysician  must  not  regard  thought  as 
a  necessary  evil,  a  limitation  of  his  power  to  engulf  himself 
in  the  real,  but  rather  as  an  indispensable  element  in  the 
solution  of  his  problem.  He  cannot  amputate  the  real 
world  from  his  thought  about  it.  If  he  could,  his  success 
would  result  in  a  sort  of  intellectual  suicide,  for  the  world 
thus  obtained  would  no  longer  be  the  world  which  meta 
physics  seeks  to  represent  to  itself.  It  would  no  longer  be 
the  whole.  Therein  lies  the  source  of  the  falsity  which 
Fouillee  ascribes  to  the  systems  of  exclusive  materialism 
and  exclusive  idealism,  and  likewise  to  exclusive  intellec- 
tualism  and  exclusive  voluntarism. 

In  the  construction  of  a  monism  based  on  consciousness 
as  the  fundamental  type  of  existence,  Fouillee  endeavors  to 
prove  that  force  is  an  element  in  all  facts  of  consciousness. 
He  uses  *  force'  in  a  sense  larger  than  that  conveyed  by 
mechanics.  From  the  point  of  view  of  mechanical  science, 


102  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

there  are  only  movements  and  mathematical  formulas  ex 
pressing  the  succession  of  these  movements.  There  are  no 
forces.  Force,  activity,  efficient  causality,  all  these  are 
terms  that  are  excluded  from  mechanics  as  much  as  from 
logic.  An  explanation  of  psychological  facts  which  is  guided 
by  the  principle  omnia  mecanice  fiunt  is  only  partially  true. 
Where  we  deal  with  physical  or  physiological  facts,  such  as 
cerebral  activity,  we  remain  in  the  realm  of  mechanism. 
But  facts  of  consciousness  may  not  be  thus  dismissed.  There 
must  be  a  mean  term  between  the  mechanical  action  of  the 
milieu  upon  consciousness  and  the  representational  character 
of  so-called  'pure'  intellection.  Such  a  mean  term  is  found 
in  the  appetitive  process,  at  once  mental  and  mechanical, 
since  it  consists  of  the  three  moments,  sensation,  emotion, 
and  motor  reaction.  It  contains  all  the  necessary  elements 
for  the  explanation  of  both  automatic,  mechanical  move 
ments  and  simple,  voluntary  movements.  Movement,  force, 
activity,  or  whatever  it  be  called,  is  thus  restored  to  a  mental 
basis.  The  psychical  and  the  mechanical  are  not  two  as 
pects.  They  are  one  single  reality  which  is  revealed  to 
itself  in  appetite  by  direct  and  immediate  revelation.  Con 
scious  activity  is  psychical.  It  is  the  appetitive  and  percep 
tive  nature  of  consciousness  which  renders  it  capable  of 
producing  changes.  Whether  its  activity  shall  evolve  toward 
mechanical  action,  on  one  hand,  or  toward  willed  action, 
on  the  other,  is  simply  a  question  of  the  diminution  or  in 
crease  of  consciousness.  Its  relation  to  the  brain  is  one  of 
collaboration,  not  of  parallelism. 

It  is  mainly  in  his  Psychologic  des  idees-forces  (1893),  a 
two-volume  work  of  great  importance  in  the  realm  of  volun- 
taristic  psychology,  that  Fouillee  expounds  the  theory  of 
the  appetitive  process  which  is  fundamental  to  his  principle 
of  thought-forces.  There  are  also  a  number  of  valuable 
statements  of  the  doctrine  in  other  works,  notably  in  his 
Evolutionisme  des  idees-forces  (1890),  the  Introduction  to 
which  furnishes  a  succinct  summary  of  his  synthetic  philos 
ophy,  and  in  La  morale  des  idees-forces  (1908),  which  de 
velops  its  ethical  aspect. 


FOUILLEE'S  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  103 

The  appetitive  process,  in  brief,  is  a  process  of  external 
action  and  internal  reaction.  Even  in  the  most  rudimentary 
consciousness,  according  to  Fouillee,  there  appear  three 
terms:  (i)  Some  sort  of  discernment,  whereby  a  being  per 
ceives  his  changes  of  state;  (2)  some  sort  of  well-being  or 
ill-being,  wherein  he  is  not  indifferent  to  the  changes;  (3) 
some  sort  of  reaction,  which  is  the  germ  of  choice  or  prefer 
ence.  As  soon  as  the  process  reaches  the  stage  of  reflection 
upon  itself,  it  constitutes  the  'idea,'  which  Fouillee  takes 
in  the  Cartesian  and  Spinozistic  sense,  he  says,  "as  a  dis 
cernment  inseparable  from  a  preference."  l  From  discern 
ment  there  is  born  intelligence;  and  from  preference,  will. 
The  idea  is  thus  an  internal  revelation  of  an  energy  and  of 
its  point  of  application. 

The  appetitive  process  is  thus  seen  to  determine  the 
character  of  the  intellectual  element  in  consciousness. 
4 Pure'  intellection  is  an  abstraction.  Every  conscious  state 
is  an  'idea'  in  so  far  as  it  is  apprehension;  but  it  is  also  a 
'force,'  because  it  involves  a  preference,  or  a  form  of  willing. 
No  'idea'  can  be  a  mere  static  representation  of  an  object, 
a  picture  projected  from  an  external  world  into  the  camera 
obscura  of  the  mind.  If  ideas  could  be  so  acquired,  they 
would  be  the  resultants  of  the  action  of  the  object  upon  the 
brain  of  the  subject,  which  would  be  a  biological,  not  a  psy 
chological,  phenomenon.  Taking  the  word  'idea'  in  a  larger 
sense  than  that  connoted  by  its  representative  aspect  alone, 
Fouillee  is  able  to  emphasize  the  oneness  of  the  mental  life 
to  a  degree  which  is  impossible  for  any  philosopher  who 
would  erect  into  an  absolute  a  single  element  of  the  threefold 
process  rooted  in  appetition. 

The  same  mutual  implication  of  these  three  elements  is 
shown  in  Fouillee's  discovery  of  the  "foundation  of  exist 
ence  "  in  the  principle,  volonte  de  conscience,  which  is  the 
phrase  most  used  in  his  later  works  to  designate  his  synthesis 
of  voluntarism  and  intellectualism.  He  chose  the  expres 
sion  "volonte  de"  in  conscious  contrast  with  the  various 
presentations  of  voluntarism  which  have  followed  Schopen- 
1  Psychologic  des  idees-forces,  Vol.  I,  p.  ix. 


104  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

hauer's  theory  of  the  will.  His  opposition  to  these  philoso 
phies  of  the  will  is  based  on  the  same  objection  as  his  opposi 
tion  to  a  'pure'  intellectualism,  namely,  that  they  erect  into 
an  absolute  some  one  particular  manifestation  of  will.  The 
total  activity  of  the  will  includes  all  such  partial  manifesta 
tions  as  the  'will  for  power,'  the  'will  for  life,'  and  the  will 
for  practical  'activity.'  Their  relation  to  the  'will  for  con 
sciousness'  is  that  of  part  to  whole. 

The  conscious  subject  wills  to  be  pour  soi.  That  is  to 
say,  he  wills  to  be  as  conscious  as  possible.  The  maximum 
of  consciousness  involves  the  maximum  of  its  elements, 
thought,  feeling,  and  action.  The  intimate  union  of  these 
three  elements  has  been  discovered  in  the  appetitive  process 
underlying  the  law  of  idees-forces.  It  is  but  a  further  de 
velopment  of  the  same  theory  of  the  will  which  appears 
here  as  "one  will  with  three  functions."  The  correspondence 
of  the  three  functions,  intelligence,  jouissance,  and  puissance, 
to  the  former  trinity  indicates  at  once  their  psychological 
origin. 

The  first  function,  intelligence,  is  derived  from  the  psy 
chological  relation  of  subject  and  object.  The  conscious 
subject  is  in  perpetual  relation  with  other  subjects,  whence 
arises  a  feeling  of  difference,  a  distinction  between  the 
'self  and  the  'non-self.'  The  genesis  of  this  idea  of  self 
is  explained  by  the  formation  of  centers  in  consciousness 
which  end  by  being  called  'I,'  'you,'  'he,'  'it,'  etc.  "Con 
sciousness  spontaneously  polarizes  itself,"  says  Fouillee, 
"and  the  two  poles  are  the  willed  and  the  non-willed."  1 
The  idea  of  self,  when  once  formed,  becomes  a  center  of 
gravitation,  seeking  to  make  other  beings  its  means  of 
action,  feeling,  and  increase  of  consciousness.  As  intelligence 
grows,  the  modification  of  the  subject's  consciousness  be 
comes  another  object,  through  the  spontaneous  judgment 
of  discrimination.  That  is  the  dawn  of  reflection.  Reflec 
tion  inevitably  turns  inward  upon  the  activity  of  the  con 
scious  subject,  to  discover  within  the  functions  of  conscious 
ness  the  dynamic  character  of  reality.  Intelligence  implies 
1  Psychologie  des  idtes-jorces.  Vol.  II,  p.  18. 


FOUILLEE'S  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  105 

the  relation  of  consciousness  and  the  world,  and  this  re- 
latedness  is  present  from  the  beginning.  Objectivity  is 
inherent  in  subjectivity  itself.1  The  problem  is  no  longer 
the  question,  Does  the  subject  exist?  but,  How  does  it  act? 
The  conscious  self  is  never  solitaire  but  always  solidaire, 
because  its  functions  of  thinking,  feeling,  and  acting  all  im 
ply  the  ceaseless  action  and  reaction  of  subject  and  object. 
Neither  subject  nor  object  can  be  comprehended  by  itself. 
To  be  intelligent  at  all  is  to  be  in  relation,  in  action  and 
reaction,  with  an  object. 

The  second  function  of  the  will-for-consciousness,  la 
jouissance,  or  sensibility,  is  almost  equally  significant  for  a 
synthesis  of  intellectualism  and  voluntarism,  for  it  links  the 
other  two  functions  together  in  a  manner  that  renders  their 
union  more  intelligible.  Briefly,  the  subject  acts  with  an 
enjoyment  both  of  his  activity  and  of  the  idea  that  directs 
it.  In  fact,  Fouillee  goes  even  further  than  this  and  remarks 
that,  "Without  this  immanent  jotiissance,  he  would  not 
act  at  all."  2  Such  a  function  is  indispensable  to  ethical 
activity,  and  it  is  in  the  field  of  ethics  that  Fouillee  develops 
its  possibilities  most  fully.  He  does  not  arrive  at  hedonism 
in  following  out  the  relation  of  pleasure  and  activity,  but 
maintains  consistently  that  the  act  is  done  for  its  own  sake. 
It  is  not  done  for  pleasure  but  it  is  always  done  with  pleasure. 
In  La  morale  des  idees-forces  he  shows  us  how  moral  activity 
is  governed  by  a  "persuasive  ideal"  instead  of  by  an  abstract 
imperative.  We  are  drawn,  not  driven,  toward  morality. 
The  more  joy  there  is  in  moral  behavior,  the  more  moral  it  is, 
and  the  greater  the  idee-force  of  the  ideal.  But  because  this 
jouissance  is  rooted  in  the  will-for-consciousness  and  is  in- 
dissolubly  connected  with  intelligence,  we  find  that  it  is  at 
once  subjective  and  objective.  The  intelligence  cannot  com 
prehend  without  enjoying,  nor  enjoy  without  comprehending, 
its  objects.  We  have  here,  then,  an  intellectual  joy  which 
carries  with  it  its  own  impulsive  power  through  its  connection 
with  the  third  function  of  consciousness,  and  which  is  at 
once  an  idee-force  and  an  idee-joie.  The  subject-object  rela- 
1  La  pensee,  p.  27.  2  La  morale  des  idees-forces,  p.  123. 


106  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

tion  involves  either  the  acceptance  or  the  rejection  of  obli 
gation,  but  in  this  respect,  too,  Fouillee  finds  the  will  fun 
damentally  in  agreement  with  the  intelligence.  He  finds 
obligation  to  be  a  persuasion  of  the  will  by  the  intellect, 
constituted  by  a  spontaneous  expansion  of  both  intelligence 
and  will.  When  the  individual  will  expands  toward  the 
universal,  as  it  constantly  tends  to  do,  there  may  arise  a 
feeling  of  obligation  which  is  clothed  with  the  authority  of 
an  imperative,  but  it  is  not  primarily  an  imperative.  It  is 
an  idee-force  derived  from  the  content  of  the  moral  ideal, 
which  excites  in  us  an  idee-joie  simultaneously  with  the 
'ought.'  It  is  only  when  the  expansion  of  the  will  is  opposed 
by  obstacles  that  the  ideal  cherished  by  the  will  becomes  an 
ought.  Left  to  its  natural  development,  the  will  would  need 
no  'must'  to  thrust  obligation  upon  it.  Obligation  is  sec 
ondary  to  the  supreme  persuasive,  which  operates  not  by 
virtue  of  necessity  and  constraint  but  by  virtue  of  their 
progressive  disappearance.  In  this  conception  of  the  free 
man  as  one  whose  will  is  at  one  with  the  will  of  the  universe, 
Fouillee  approaches  the  grandeur  and  simplicity  of  Spinoza's 
philosophy. 

The  third  function,  la  puissance,  is  the  tendency  toward 
realization  which  was  emphasized  by  Fouillee  as  early  as 
1872  in  La  liberte  et  la  determinism*.  Taken  here  as  a  func 
tion  of  the  will-for-consciousness,  it  signifies  that  elan  en 
avant  which  has  just  been  called  the  expansion  of  conscious 
ness  toward  universality.  In  this  spontaneous  expansion 
we  find  the  explanation  of  evolution  itself.  It  is  the  struggle 
of  the  will-for-consciousness  to  be  as  greatly  increased  as 
possible,  to  expand  toward  infinity.  There  is  no  equilibrium 
in  the  mental  world,  no  conservation  of  energy,  because 
etre  must  also  be  plus-etre.  Because  of  the  conscious  power 
which  characterizes  voluntary  activity,  individuals  endowed 
with  it  tend  to  "persevere  in  their  own  being,"  as  Spinoza  ex 
presses  the  same  thought;  and  the  universal  will-for-conscious 
ness  tends  to  expand  into  that  indefinite  development  which 
constitutes  revolution  novatrice.  Evolution  is  always  en  train 
de  se  faire.  It  is  in  this  that  the  essence  of  power  consists. 


FOUILLEE'S  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  107 

Although  the  language  of  Fouillee  suggests  the  philosophy 
of  evolution  developed  later  by  Bergson,  who  dwells  upon 
the  creative  force  of  the  elan  vital,  there  are  fundamental 
differences  in  the  two  points  of  view.  Both  Fouillee  and 
Bergson  are  ranked  with  the  voluntarists,  but  Bergson's 
voluntarism  seems  to  have  descended  from  the  spiritualistic 
activism  of  Maine  de  Biran  and  to  have  become  imbued  with 
the  doctrines  of  spiritual  liberty  and  radical  contingency  that 
dominate  the  theories  of  Ravaisson  and  Boutroux.  Fouillee's 
voluntarism,  on  the  other  hand,  departs  from  the  line  of 
direct  descent  and  develops  the  tendency  found  in  Taine's 
intellectualism.  There  is  the  same  insistence  upon  coherence 
and  the  same  synthesis  of  those  psychological  elements  which 
are  usually  divorced  from  one  another  in  anti-intellectualistic 
voluntarism.  In  Taine,  as  in  Fouillee,  the  essential  connec 
tion  of  motor  elements  and  ideational  elements  in  our  mental 
life  is  strongly  emphasized.  In  Bergson  there  is  a  basic 
division  between  these  elements.  At  the  very  outset  of 
their  evolution,  according  to  Bergson,  thought  and  move 
ment  parted  company.  The  original  elan  of  consciousness 
developed  in  two  directions,  instinct  and  intellect.  Instinct 
remained  identified  with  the  spontaneous  activity  of  life; 
intellect  merely  looks  upon  life  from  the  outside.  Intellect, 
then,  must  ally  itself  with  a  mechanistic  explanation  of  the 
universe.  Intellect  may  make  itself  tools,  or  mechanical 
instruments  for  measuring  and  computing,  but  it  can  never 
enter  into  the  heart  of  reality  and  know  life  as  it  is.  It  may 
formulate  sciences  but  it  can  never  comprehend  anything 
save  the  inert  and  lifeless.  It  is  identified  with  matter;  and 
matter  and  life,  or  matter  and  mind,  are  found  by  Bergson 
to  be  a  dualism.  Dualism  in  any  form  seems  to  Fouillee  to 
be  artificial.  He  declines  to  accept  as  philosophy  a  view  of 
life  which  cuts  it  in  two,  puts  instinct  and  feeling  on  one 
side  and  intellect  and  idea  on  the  other.  He  repudiates  the 
bifurcation  of  the  evolutional  elan  by  means  of  which  Bergson 
opposes  the  psychical  and  the  physical,  the  temporal  and  the 
spatial,  the  intuitive  and  the  intelligible,  the  quick  and  the 
dead. 


108  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

Fouillee  gives  a  much  more  satisfactory  account  of  in 
telligence  and  its  evolution  than  Bergson;  without  employing 
dichotomies,  he  demonstrates  the  indissoluble  union  of 
thought  and  movement  in  their  common  source,  appetition. 
His  doctrine  of  will  as  the  ultimate  reality  revealed  to  itself 
in  consciousness  involves  a  recognition  of  the  psychical 
character  of  force,  and  consequently  a  recognition  of  the 
psychical  element  in  natural  forces.  Idealism  and  naturalism 
may  then  be  reconciled,  for  both  will  find  a  mean  term  in  the 
psychological  nature  of  reality.  The  functional  unity  of  the 
mental  and  the  physical  in  appetition  makes  it  impossible 
to  erect  either  into  an  absolute,  and  likewise  renders  a  double 
flow  of  the  life  impulse  absurd.  " There  are  no  more  two 
evolutions  in  us  than  there  are  two  or  three  distinct  facul 
ties."  l  The  very  term,  'life-impulse,'  seems  to  Fouillee  to 
be  used  in  a  vague  and  irrational  manner  by  Bergson,  to 
denote  something  which  eludes  the  clear-cut  expressions  of 
a  conceptual  philosophy,  because  it  is  itself  formless  and  in 
conceivable, — "  a  romantic  name  for  unintelligibility."  That 
this  formless  impulse  may  be  divined  by  intuition  is  true 
only  in  so  far  as  intuition  is  at  one  with  the  intellect;  for  the 
intuitive  sympathy  which  enters  into  reality  and  ' lives  it'  is 
helpless  either  to  gain  or  to  impart  its  priceless  knowledge 
without  the  categories,  which  are  but  "  abstracts  of  our 
selves,  generalized  and  universalized."  In  Fouillee's  met 
aphysics  the  categories  of  the  will-for-consciousness  are  not 
points  of  view  but  points  of  contact,  or  identities  between 
the  intelligible  and  the  real.2  All  of  them  are  necessary  to 
intuitive  knowledge,  with  the  possible  exception  of  causality. 
Causality  is  excepted  by  Fouillee  because,  as  he  ironically 
observes,  "  Intuition  is  like  ecstasy  in  never  raising  the  ques 
tion,  Why?  That  is  what  makes  it  so  little  philosophical." 

In  Fouillee's  attitude  toward  intuitionism  as  an  inter 
pretation  of  the  universe  there  is  to  be  found  a  vigorous 
restatement  of  his  abhorrence  of  one-sidedness  in  philosophy. 
It  would  not  involve  a  long  search  to  discover  in  his  works 

1  La  pensee,  Preface,  p.  xi. 

2  Esquisse  (Fune  interpretation  du  monde,  p.  158. 


FOUILLEE'S  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  109 

passages  in  which  he  deplores  the  unilateral  views  of  con 
ceptual  philosophy  quite  as  earnestly  as  he  here  deplores 
the  lack  of  concepts  in  Bergson's  intuitionism.     It  is  not 
inconsistency,  however,  that  appears  in  this  critical  inter 
pretation,  to  which  he  devotes  nearly  one  hundred  pages 
in  La  pensee  et  les  nouvelles  ecoles  anti-intellectualistes.    Both 
concepts  and  intuitions  are  partial,  unilateral  views  of  the 
whole;  but  concepts  prove  to  have  a  scientific  and  philo 
sophical  value  which  intuitions  lack.     It  would  be  vain  to 
urge  that  science  is  outside  the  realm  of  intuition  and  that 
intuition  therefore  need  not  concern  itself  with  the  applica 
bility  of  its  findings  to  science,  for  it  is  just  in  respect  to 
scientific  exploration  that  an  enlightened  intuition  is  most 
brilliantly  exhibited.     It  is  because  the  kind  of  intuitions 
which  Bergson  describes  are  not  enlightened  that  they  are 
useless  for  philosophy  as  well  as  for  science.     When  intui 
tions  confine  themselves  to  obscure  feelings,  affections,  emo 
tions,   and  vague   divinations,   they   may  have   a   psycho- 
physiological  value,  but  they  have  no  value  for  philosophy 
until  controlled  and  interpreted  by  reason.    They  must  be 
universalized  or  they  remain  mere  sudden  and  spontaneous 
revelations  of  that  which  is  transitory:  intuitions  without 
the  tueri  and  without  the  in.     To  become  useful  for  our 
interpretations  of  reality,  they  must  enter  into  a  synthesis 
with  concepts  and  all  other  partial  approaches  to  knowl 
edge;  they  must  become  unified  in  consciousness  and  ex 
pressed  in  intelligence.     Intuitionism  rightly  appeals  to  the 
most  immediate  possible  consciousness,  but  it  wrongly  at 
tributes  to  this  immediate  consciousness   a  mass  of  data 
which  are  really  only  ulterior  concepts.    Conceptual  philos 
ophy,  on  the  other  hand,  rightly  sees  in  ideas  the  formulas 
of  relations  appertaining  to  the  real,  but  it  wrongly  wanders 
into  abstractions.    Both  views  are  needed,  in  so  far  as  both 
contain  true  elements,  but  neither  must  be  regarded  as  suf 
ficient  in  itself.     Of  the  two  methods,  intuitionism  seems 
the  less  able  to  serve  philosophy,  because  it  is  fore-ordained 
to  be  mute,  and  the  human  mind  can  gather  very  little  solace 
from  an  oracle  that  is  dumb.    Fouillee's  own  condemnation 


1 10  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

is  more  sweeping  than  this,  and  even  more  so  than  Kant's 
famous  epigram.  He  says  that  intuitions  without  concepts 
are  not  merely  blind;  they  are  non-existent. 

Another  phase  of  the  divergence  in  the  evolutional  doc 
trines  of  these  two  noted  voluntarists  is  disclosed  in  their 
radically  different  theories  of  the  relation  of  instinct  and 
intelligence.  Fouillee's  account  is  the  earlier  and  more  satis 
factory.  Both  instinct  and  intelligence  have  their  basis  in 
appetite,  which  has  been  shown  to  form  the  intermediate 
stage  between  reflective  thought  and  brute  mechanism. 
Having  the  same  origin,  instinct  is  not  different  in  kind, 
but  in  degree  of  consciousness,  from  intellect.  In  the  be 
ginning  of  conscious  life  motor  reaction  is  inseparable  from 
the  conscious  excitation.  Habit  and  heredity  tend  to  or 
ganize  the  mechanical  structure  of  an  animal  in  such  a 
way  that  consciousness  and  appetite  are  less  and  less  needed 
to  instigate  or  direct  each  repetition  of  the  act.  Since 
natural  selection  will  eliminate  whatever  is  not  useful,  the 
utility  of  an  act  need  not  be  represented  beforehand.  The 
inevitable  accompaniment  of  pleasure  or  pain  serves  to 
impel  reaction  quite  as  readily  as  would  an  intellectual 
representation  of  an  end  to  be  served.  The  directive  idea 
is  virtually  preformed  in  the  structure  of  an  organism,  and 
it  becomes  actual  under  the  influence  of  sensations,  emo 
tions,  and  appetitions.  An  instinct  is  neither  a  transformed 
mechanism  nor  a  lapsed  intelligence,  but  a  transformed 
appetite.  Intelligence  itself  is  this  same  appetite,  become 
more  and  more  progressive  and  reflective,  until  it  takes  the 
form  of  a  superior  instinct,  a  superior  adaptation  to  a  larger 
milieu.1  In  his  later  statements  of  the  same  topic,  Fouillee 
reiterates  the  fundamental  likeness  between  all  forms  of 
conscious  activity.  Instinct  and  intuition  are  no  nearer 
the  heart  of  reality  than  is  intelligence,  nor  are  they  any  the 
less  utilitarian.  To  say  that  the  intellect  falsifies  the  real, 
as  Bergson  does,  is  to  misunderstand  the  nature  of  the  real 
as  well  as  the  nature  of  the  intellect. 

It  is  a  presupposition  of  modern  philosophy  that  reality 
1  ttvolutionisme  des  id€es-forces,  pp.  209-229. 


FOUILLEE'S  INTELLECTUALISTIC  VOLUNTARISM  III 

is  intelligible.  Experience  is  possible  for  the  knowing  sub 
ject  because  the  mind  has  points  of  contact  with  the  object 
known.  A  psychological  theory  of  reality  such  as  Fouillee's 
is  never  in  opposition  to  a  logical  interpretation  of  the  na 
ture  of  things,  because  subject  and  object  are  unable  to 
sever  their  relation  of  functional  unity.  The  intellection 
of  the  real  is  the  highest  effort  of  that  will  which  is  the  foun 
dation  of  our  being.  "Intelligence,  immanent  in  the  life 
of  instinct,  and  not  externally  patched  upon  it,  is  unable 
not  to  pursue  its  exercise,  which  is  knowledge;  its  object, 
which  is  reality;  its  law,  which  is  truth;  or  its  development, 
which  is  indefinite  progress  toward  the  real  and  the  true."  1 
Philosophy  is  thus  the  idee-force  of  reality  itself. 

1  La  pensee,  p.  31. 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA 
EDGAR  LENDERSON  HINMAN 

THE  attempts  of  western  philosophy  to  formulate  a 
thorough-going  system  of  idealistic  monism  have  persistently 
suggested  to  many  minds  the  substantial  identity  of  such  a 
mode  of  thought  with  the  philosophical  pantheism  of  India. 
To  some  thinkers  the  suggestion  has  been  distinctly  a  con 
genial  one,  and  it  has  been  gladly  fostered  by  such  writers  as 
Schopenhauer,  Max  Miiller,  and  Paul  Deussen.  The  repre 
sentatives  of  the  Hegelian  tendency,  however,  have  in 
general  repelled  this  view.  They  are  willing  to  strike  hands 
with  Spinoza,  it  is  true,  provided  a  certain  rendering  of 
Spinozism  is  pushed  into  the  foreground;  but  the  regular 
exponents  of  the  Vedanta  quite  commonly  draw  their  fire. 
Perhaps  the  Hindu  scholars  are  less  hesitant  to  admit  kin 
ship.  Certain  of  them,  at  any  rate,  aim  to  commend  Ve- 
dantism  to  western  thought  by  urging  its  essential  identity 
with  the  Absolute  Idealism  of  the  Hegelian  school. 

But  whatever  the  representatives  of  western  monistic 
idealism  themselves  may  say,  their  critics  and  the  educated 
public  in  general  seem  to  feel  that  there  is  probably  a  great 
deal  of  truth  in  the  charge  that  they  are  essentially  panthe 
ists  of  the  orthodox  Brahmanical  type.  The  assertion  is  an 
old  one,  of  course,  but  perhaps  no  other  single  contention 
has  functioned  more  largely  than  this  in  the  recent  out 
burst  of  criticism  against  all  forms  of  Absolute  Idealism  that 
have  learned  anything  from  Hegel.  Pragmatist  and  Berg- 
sonian  writers,  in  particular,  have  made  a  large  handling 
of  it,  and  it  is  scattered  at  large  throughout  philosophical 
literature. 

At  the  same  time,  a  thoughtful  reader  is  impressed  that 
this  charge,  in  the  form  commonly  found  in  recent  philo 
sophical  discussion,  is  quite  loose  and  indefinite.  It  regularly 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  113 

dispenses  with  all  analysis  and  is  too  indiscriminating  con 
cerning  the  exact  meaning  of  the  doctrines  which  it  is  striv 
ing  to  identify.  Indeed,  the  precise  sense  in  which  they 
may  be  identified  is  normally  left  vague. 

The  critic  can  hardly  be  understood  to  allege,  of  course, 
that  the  two  philosophies  are  flatly  one  and  the  same.  The 
enormous  differences  in  point  of  historical  setting,  method, 
goal,  internal  development,  and  cultural  results  preclude 
such  a  suggestion.  He  must  mean,  then,  that  in  spite  of  the 
obvious  differences  which  separate  two  great  historical  sys 
tems  of  thought,  there  are  similarities  on  certain  issues  which 
are  of  so  great  importance  that  in  comparison  with  them 
other  differences  are  dwarfed.  The  issue  becomes,  then,  one 
of  decision  concerning  dominating  significance;  and  this 
needs  to  be  much  more  accurately  defined  and  argued  than 
is  usually  done. 

Further,  the  careful  student  is  impressed  that  the  writers 
who  urge  this  identification  uniformly  omit  to  make  an 
analysis  of  the  meaning  and  interpretation  of  Vedantism 
and  to  discriminate  the  different  schools  in  its  development. 
And  yet  that  is  of  the  utmost  importance  to  any  fruitful  dis 
cussion  of  this  matter.  There  exist  many  different  editings 
of  the  Vedanta.  Two,  in  particular,  have  attained  to  marked 
prominence.  The  followers  of  Sankara  present  an  abstract 
monism  that  is  frankly  and  avowedly  pantheistic,  perhaps 
the  only  Simon-pure  pantheism  that  the  world  has  ever  seen. 
The  party  of  Ramanuga,  on  the  other  hand,  present  monism 
in  quite  a  different  light,  a  concrete  monism,  one  may  say, 
which  would  seem  to  be  rather  more  theistic  than  pantheis 
tic.  Both  are  Vedanta;  both  rest  upon  a  philosophical  inter 
pretation  of  the  Vedas,  the  Upanishads,  and  the  Vedanta- 
sutras.  Now  a  comparison  with  Hegelianism  which  holds 
good  of  one  of  these  lines  of  development  may  not  and  often 
does  not  hold  of  the  other  at  all. 

Is  Hegelianism  like  the  Vedanta?  That  depends  upon 
whose  Vedanta  one  is  talking  about.  If  the  Vedanta  of 
Sankara  is  under  discussion, — the  pantheistic  Vedanta,  the 
world's  arch  representative  of  abstract  monism, — then  the 


114  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

present  writer  is  convinced  that  the  two  philosophies  are 
essentially  unlike,  and  are  even  opposed.  But  if  the  reference 
is  to  the  Vedanta  of  Ramanuga, — the  Vedanta  of  neo- 
Brahmanic  reform,  of  Vishnuite  theism  rather  than  orthodox 
Brahmanic  pantheism, — then  it  would  seem  that,  in  spite  of 
obvious  differences,  the  similarities  are  so  genuine  and  sig 
nificant  that  the  two  may  be  regarded  as  essentially  similar 
in  their  philosophical  import.  I  should  like  to  develop  this 
view,  so  far  as  somewhat  narrow  space  limits  make  possible. 

The  factors  which  argue  for  the  easy  identification  of 
Hegelianism  with  the  orthodox  presentation  of  Brahmanism 
may  be  hastily  surveyed.  They  are:  the  strongly  marked 
negative  movement  in  each,  whereby  everything  that  is 
limited  and  finite  is  branded  as  unreal;  the  radical  monism, 
whereby  the  Absolute  alone  is  regarded  as  truly  real;  and 
especially,  the  doctrine  of  the  Universal  Self,  according  to 
which  every  finite  mind  is  vitally  one  with  the  Infinite 
Spirit,  and  finds  its  *  truth'  and  its  good  in  coming  to  the 
consciousness  of  that  union.  And  when  these  things  have 
been  said,  the  case  seems  to  many  minds  to  be  really  closed. 

But  "when  two  men  say  the  same  thing,  yet  are  they  not 
the  same."  A  discriminating  study  will  show,  I  think,  that 
each  of  these  fundamental  teachings  bears  a  quite  different 
significance  in  western  monism  from  that  intended  by  San- 
kara,  and  that  the  differences  are  really  the  matter  of  capital 
importance  in  the  comparison.  In  order  to  bring  out  such 
differences,  we  may  make  a  brief  analysis  of  the  two  philos 
ophies,  especially  in  regard  to  (I)  the  method  by  which  each 
is  controlled,  (II)  the  doctrine  of  appearance  which  results, 
and  (III)  the  doctrine  of  the  Absolute  Self  and  its  signif 
icance  for  the  finite  individual. 


I 

The  method  which  is  prevailingly  used  in  the  Vedanta, 
and  which  comes  to  its  climax  in  the  speculation  of  Sankara, 
is  that  of  a  pure  and  unrelieved  abstractionism  which  neg 
lects  or  negates  all  differences.  One  could  assemble  from  the 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  115 

sacred  literature  pages  on  pages  of  passages  which  commend 
this  method,  passages  which  have  become  famous  in  Hindu 
discussion. 

Thus,  in  the  Khandogya-Upanishad,  we  read: 
"My  dear,  as  by  one  clod  of  clay  all  that  is  made  of  clay 
is  known,  the  difference  being  only  a  name,  arising  from 
speech,  but  the  truth  being  that  all  is  clay; 

"And  as,  my  dear,  by  one  nugget  of  gold  all  that  is  made 
of  gold  is  known,  the  difference  being  only  a  name,  arising 
from  speech,  but  the  truth  being  that  all  is  gold; 

"And  as,  my  dear,  by  one  pair  of  nail-scissors  all  that  is 
made  of  iron  is  known,  the  difference  being  only  a  name, 
arising  from  speech,  but  the  truth  being  that  all  is  iron, — 
such,  my  dear,  is  that  instruction." 

This,  then,  is  the  central  account  of  the  method  "by  which 
we  hear  what  cannot  be  heard,  by  which  we  perceive  what 
cannot  be  perceived,  by  which  we  know  what  cannot  be 
known."  2  It  is  the  quest  of  the  universal,  it  is  true,  but  of 
a  universal  defined  in  a  purely  negative  way,  by  the  simple 
process  of  throwing  away  all  differences. 

"Where  one  sees  nothing  else,  hears  nothing  else,  under 
stands  nothing  else,  that  is  the  Infinite.  Where  one  sees 
something  else,  hears  something  else,  understands  something 
else,  that  is  the  finite." 

"Sir,  in  what  does  the  Infinite  rest?" 
"In  its  own  greatness — or  not  even  in  greatness."  3 
A  passage  in  the  Brihadaranyaka-Upanishad  carries  this 
method  up  to  the  non-duality  standpoint  of  Sankara:  "For 
when  there  is  as  it  were  duality,  then  one  sees  the  other, 
one  smells  the  other,  one  tastes  the  other,  one  salutes  the 
other,  one  hears  the  other,  one  perceives  the  other,  one 
touches  the  other,  one  knows  the  other;  but  when  the  Self 
only  is  all  this,  how  should  he  see  another,  how  should  he 
smell  another,  how  should  he  taste  another,  how  should  he 
salute  another,  how  should  he  hear  another,  how  should  he 
touch  another,  how  should  he  know  another?  How  should 

1  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  I,  pp.  Q2f . 

2  Ibid.,  p.  92.  *  Ibid.,  p.  123. 


Ii6  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

he  know  Him  by  whom  he  knows  all  this?  That  Self  is  to 
be  described  by  No,  No!"  l 

It  was  on  this  basis,  then,  that  Sankara  founded  his  ex 
planation  of  Vedanta  as  advaita, — non-duality, — radical, 
abstract  monism.  He  must  at  once  admit  the  authoritative- 
ness  of  a  sacred  literature  which  was  somewhat  popular  in 
its  thought,  and  therefore  penetrated  by  complex  and  in 
consistent  motives,  and  also  bring  everything  to  a  rational 
interpretation  in  terms  of  philosophical  conceptions  con 
sistent  with  a  high  order  of  reflection.  He  dealt  with  the 
problem  by  grasping  firmly  the  logic  of  abstraction  as  his 
controlling  method,  and  purposed  to  accept  rigorously  the 
results  in  which  it  would  issue.  But  the  situation,  which  is 
really  unworkable  at  the  best,  would  have  been  obviously 
impossible,  if  he  had  not  called  to  his  service  a  distinction 
between  two  orders  of  philosophical  knowledge.  The  higher 
order  (para  vidya)  was  supposed  to  afford  the  true  Vedantic 
insight,  the  teaching  of  absolute  non-duality.  All  elements 
of  difference  or  distinction  being  then  illusory,  the  Absolute 
stands  as  a  blank,  characterless  unity.  The  lower  order  of 
knowledge  (apard  vidya),  although  still  speculative,  is  the 
level  at  which  the  Upanishads  normally  move.  Here  the 
writers  speak  of  the  Universal  Self,  indeed,  but  ascribe  to  it 
thoughts  and  purposes,  creative  activity,  and  various  char 
acteristics  and  relations  to  man.  Now  all  these  modes  of 
expression  of  the  lower  knowledge  must,  in  the  opinion  of 
Sankara,  be  regarded  as  symbolical.  In  the  philosophical 
sense  they  convey  no  truth  whatever.  They  may  be  em 
ployed,  however,  so  far  as  their  use  serves  to  suggest  the 
true,  undifferentiated  Brahman.  Sankara  supports  himself 
by  such  Upanishad  passages  as,  "He  is  not  this,  not  this," 
"Without  parts,  without  action,  restful,  faultless,  stainless," 
and  many  more.  And  yet  after  all,  his  real  defence  in  making 
this  distinction  is  in  his  clear  consciousness  of  the  necessary 
drift  of  an  abstractionist  logic. 

"If  you  assert  that  Brahman  must  have  manifold  powers 
[the  actual  contention  of  Vishnuite  theism],  because,  ac- 
1  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  XV,  p.  185. 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  117 

cording  to  the  scripture,  it  is  the  cause  of  the  creation,  sub 
sistence,  and  extinction  of  the  world,  we  say  No!  For  the 
passages  of  scripture  which  deny  difference  to  it  can  have 
no  other  sense  [but  the  literal  one].  But  the  passages  about 
the  creation  and  so  on  can  likewise  have  no  other  sense? 
This  is  not  so;  for  their  aim  is  [only]  to  teach  the  identity 
[of  the  world  with  Brahman].  For  when  the  scripture,  by 
the  examples  of  lumps  of  clay  and  the  like,  teaches  that  'the 
Existent,'  the  Brahman,  alone  is  true,  but  that  [its]  trans 
formation  [into  the  world]  is  untrue,  it  cannot  have  the  aim 
of  teaching  a  creation  and  the  like.  But  why  should  the 
passages  of  scripture  about  the  creation  and  the  like  be  sub 
ordinated  to  those  about  the  negation  of  differences,  and 
not  conversely  the  latter  be  subordinated  to  the  former? 
To  this  we  answer:  Because  the  passages  of  scripture  about 
the  negation  of  all  differences  have  a  meaning  which  leaves 
nothing  more  to  be  wished  for  "  1 

The  method,  then,  is  clear.  A  few  passages  in  the  sacred 
literature  meet  the  demands  of  abstractionist  logic  to  com 
pleteness;  these  therefore  are  ' higher  knowledge'  and  are 
true.  Most  passages  do  not,  and  are  therefore  not  to  be 
taken  as  true  at  all,  but  as  symbolical.  The  procedure  of 
Sankara  at  this  point  is  clearly  a  high-handed  one.  The 
man  had  not  only  the  courage  of  his  convictions,  but  also 
the  convictions  which  were  the  logical  outcome  of  his 
method. 

And  yet,  as  the  method  of  abstraction  is  essentially  an 
unsound  one,  its  difficulties  are  promptly  visited  upon  its 
devotee.  Already  in  the  Upanishads  there  is  a  passage 
which  might  have  conveyed  to  Sankara  a  different  sugges 
tion  from  the  one  he  seems  to  have  taken  from  it.  A  pupil 
addressed  to  a  master  the  request,  "Tell  me  the  Brahman." 
Then  the  master  "became  very  silent."  When  the  request 
was  urgently  reiterated,  however,  he  replied,  "I  am  telling 
Him  to  you,  but  you  do  not  understand." 

The  sage  of  the  Upanishads  would  seem  to  have  been 

1  Sankara's  Commentary  as  quoted  by  Deussen,  System  of  the  Vedanta, 
p.  no;  see  also  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  XXXVIII,  p.  395. 


Ii8  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  only  really  consistent  representative  of  Vedantic  pan 
theism  that  literature  accredits  to  us.  Any  philosopher  who 
attempts  to  expound  the  logical  meaning  of  the  doctrine 
which  turns  upon  this  method  would  have  to  "  become  very 
silent" — and  remain  so.  A  meaningless  doctrine  cannot  be 
expounded.  But  Sankara  did  not  follow  the  Upanishad 
example;  his  voluminous  writings  testify  to  that.  Through 
out  the  great  extent  of  his  expositions,  however,  he  is  mov 
ing  in  terms  of  the  Mower  order  of  knowledge.'  The  situa 
tion  which  results  is  thus  described  by  Professor  Deussen: 
"But  the  great  difficulty  for  the  philosophical  understand 
ing  of  the  Brahma-sutras  lies  in  the  fact,  that  neither  in  the 
text  nor  in  the  commentaries  are  the  two  conceptions  clearly 
separated  from  each  other,  but  rather  meet  us  everywhere 
interwoven  with  each  other,  in  such  sort  that  the  funda 
mental  texture  of  the  whole  consists  of  a  representation  of 
the  exoteric,  or,  as  we  may  call  it  (with  an  extension  of  the 
conception,  whose  justification  will  be  given  in  what  fol 
lows)  the  lower  doctrine  (apard  vidya),  which,  however,  is 
penetrated  in  every  province  by  the  esoteric  or  higher  doc 
trine  (para  vidya),  standing  in  contradiction  to  it."  * 

The  substantial  soundness  of  the  suggestion  of  Deussen 
is  apparent  to  any  critical  reader  of  Sankara's  great  Com 
mentary.  This  means,  then,  that  the  great  volume  of  his 
expositions,  to  say  nothing  of  the  text  of  the  Upanishads, 
does  not  aim  to  express  the  real  teaching  of  Sankara's  pan 
theism.  That  teaching  is  in  fact  inexpressible,  and  the  sym 
bolic  language  in  which  one  hopes  in  some  measure  to  sug 
gest  it  does  not  put  the  real  truth  of  the  matter,  not  even 
in  a  partial  degree. 

Now  of  course  the  genuine  esoteric  teaching  of  Sankara, 
after  one  has  thus  cleared  it  from  confusion  with  symbolical 
elements  that  are  not  meant  to  be  taken  seriously,  is  highly 
repugnant  to  the  Hegelian  thought.  It  is  indeed  the  deifica 
tion  of  the  abstract  category  of  Pure  Being,  destructively 
criticised  by  Hegel  in  the  Science  of  Logic  and  by  many 
other  writers  of  the  school.  That  the  Hegelians  do  not 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  98. 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  119 

mean  to  establish  such  an  outcome  will  doubtless  be  ad 
mitted  by  all.  But  that  their  method  implies  it,  and  would 
really  give  it  if  carried  out  as  remorselessly  as  with  Sankara, 
seems  still  to  be  believed  by  many.  Hegelian  reflection 
also,  it  is  urged,  is  driven  by  the  *  negativity  of  the  finite.' 
It  is  accustomed  to  set  aside  one  stage  of  existence  after 
another  as  'mere  appearance.'  It  moves  towards  an  Ab 
solute  which  is  not  only  one,  but  is  the  negative  of  every 
particular  type  of  thing  which  appears  in  our  experience. 
Wherein  then,  it  is  asked,  is  the  essential  difference? 

But  in  fact  the  method  of  the  Hegelian  philosophy  is 
widely  different  in   character   and   has   a   totally   different 
philosophical  significance  from  that  of  Sankara.     Its  con 
scious  aim,  as  is  well  known,  is  to  seek  a  reconciling  synthesis 
between  opposing  factors.     The  contesting  parties  are  not 
simply   thrown   away,   then,   as   in   the  Vedantic   scheme; 
rather,  their  vital  and  viable  elements  are  conserved  in  the 
principle  which  is  to  synthesize  them.    And  it  results  that 
the  reconciling  principle  must  always  afford  the  affirmative 
basis  for  every  characteristic  which  comes  out  in  the  finite 
factors  to  be  interpreted.     When  the  western  idealist  says 
that  the  negativity  of  thought  has  driven  him  to  a  higher 
synthetic  principle,  he  means  that  the  partisan  views  have 
not  affirmed  the  nature  of  the  real  as  profoundly  or  as  ade 
quately  as  the  fuller  reflective  thought  is  forced  to  do.    Such 
partisan  views  are  inadequate  and  require  to  be  negated; 
but  the  ground  and  significance  of  such  negative  movement 
is  to  be  found  in  the  rich  and  full  positive  nature  of  the 
real.     Now  this  view  would  seem  to  have  a  much  closer 
affinity  with  the  Vishnuite  doctrine  of  sakti,  or  manifold 
powers,  than  with  its  great  opponent,  the  orthodox  Brah- 
manical  teaching  of  non-difference.     But  its  more  genuine 
relations,  of  course,  are  with  the  Platonic  emphasis  upon 
structural  order,  rather  than  with  the  Hindu  deification  of 
the  formless;  with  the  Aristotelian  conception  of  the  perfect 
ideal  as  the  first  principle  that  energizes  all  process;  or  even 
with  Paul's  conception,  in  Colossians,  of  the  Son  who  is 
before  all  things  and  in  whom  were  all  things  made. 


120  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

To  many  writers  it  has  seemed  that  such  an  estimate  of 
the  method  of  western  Absolute  Idealism  has  become  anti 
quated  since  Mr.  Bradley's  negative  dialectic  has  taken 
its  well-known  form.  They  believe  that  the  cloven  hoof  of 
Brahmanism  is  thereby  fully  displayed.  But  this  conten 
tion  must  be  judged  unsound,  I  think,  for  two  main  reasons. 
In  the  first  place,  Mr.  Bradley's  personal  tendencies  have 
led  him  to  give  a  much  more  negative  form  to  the  discussion 
than  the  nature  of  the  case  demands;  he  is  not  a  good  in 
terpreter  of  the  conservative  or  positive  element  in  the 
method.  And  in  the  second  place,  even  those  manifold  ex 
plicit  assertions  of  a  positive  truth  in  the  order  of  finite  ex 
perience  which  are  contained  within  Appearance  and  Reality 
have  been  overlooked  or  denied  to  an  amazing  degree  by 
his  critics.  Certain  ineptitudes  of  the  author's  phraseology 
have  reinforced  certain  other  ineptitudes  of  his  genuine 
thinking  to  produce  a  reaction  that  is  out  of  all  proportion 
to  the  merits  of  the  issue.  Mr.  Bradley  is  not  nearly  so 
Brahmanistic  as  his  pragmatist  critics  allege,  but  he  seems 
to  be  somewhat  more  so  than  the  idealistic  method  would 
properly  warrant. 

Hegelian  idealism  demands,  according  to  its  historic 
formula,  the  conception  of  the  concrete  or  system-founding 
universal.  Now  one  may  indeed  urge  the  criticism  that 
such  a  conception  is  impossible,  that  all  conception  must 
involve  a  dash  of  abstraction.  But  this  is  another  story. 
To  determine  whether  such  a  contention  is  sound  or  not 
would  take  us  too  far  afield.  The  point  to  be  noticed  is, 
however,  that  the  ideal  of  a  concrete  universal,  rich  in  con 
tent,  has  been  deliberately  placed  before  the  western  idealis 
tic  monist,  and  his  method  is  adapted  to  establish  that  out 
come.  Before  Sankara,  on  the  other  hand,  stands  the  ideal 
of  an  abstract  monism,  a  universal  devoid  of  all  systematic 
content,  and  his  method  makes  any  other  outcome  impos 
sible.  If  the  conception  of  a  concrete  universal  be  not  in 
any  sense  possible,  western  idealistic  monism  may  be  a 
failure,  indeed,  but  that  is  not  saying  that  it  teaches  the 
same  thing  as  orthodox  Vedantism. 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  121 

Now  the  unorthodox  editing  of  the  Vedanta  message  by 
Ramanuga  and  his  followers  is  imbued  with  a  spirit  more 
congenial  to  western  thought.  It  is  still  monism,  to  be  sure, 
and  therefore  avails  itself  of  the  regular  Sanskrit  designation, 
non-duality  (advaita).  But  the  unity  which  it  teaches  is  one 
that  is  modified  or  qualified  by  the  inclusion  of  differentia 
tions.  This  enables  it  to  ascribe  to  finite  things,  and  espe 
cially  to  the  selves  of  men,  a  relative  reality  in  the  system 
which  the  universal  establishes  and  maintains.  The  Hindus 
call  this  visishta  advaita, — qualified  monism,  or  concrete 
monism, — a  monism  admitting  the  presence  of  genuine 
differences  within  its  unity. 

The  tendency  of  such  a  doctrine  is  towards  a  form  of 
theism  based  upon  the  philosophical  teaching  of  the  im 
manence  of  God,  to  be  sure,  but  avoiding  the  all-devouring 
consequences  of  consistent  pantheism.  It  is  by  no  accident, 
then,  that  the  Ramanugists  have  been  in  general  sym 
pathetic  with  the  philosophical  ideas  underlying  the  teaching 
of  the  neo-Brahmanical  reforming  sects.  In  their  historical 
development  as  positive  religions  these  sects  have  been  char 
acterized,  of  course,  by  many  usages  of  a  type  common  to 
all  Hinduism  and  alien  to  us,  but  their  philosophical  theology 
is  capable  of  a  high  development.  The  Vishnuite  theology, 
in  particular,  while  it  has  shown  a  remarkable  power  to  be 
come  all  things  to  all  men,  can  be  so  unfolded  as  to  present 
a  very  high  and  pure  form  of  philosophical  theism.  It  is  this 
which  has  made  the  largest  use  of  Ramanuga  and  which  his 
followers  have  aimed  to  serve. 

Professor  Thibaut 1  has  shown  that  Ramanuga's  inter 
pretation  of  Vedanta  is  as  genuinely  founded  on  the  Upan- 
ishads  and  the  Vedanta-sutras  as  is  that  of  Sankara  himself. 
It  is  unorthodox,  to  be  sure,  for  two  reasons,  neither  of  which 
impugns  its  validity.  In  the  first  place,  Sankara  lived  first, 
and  his  great  authority  had  been  established  for  perhaps  four 
centuries  when  Ramanuga  came  upon  the  scene.  As  a  con 
sequence  of  Sankara's  genius,  the  character  of  strict  Brah- 
manism  was  already  determined  before  Ramanuga  taught, 
1  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  XXXIV,  Introduction. 


122  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

and  he  could  exercise  influence  only  as  an  innovator.  In  the 
second  place,  the  abstractionist  logic  is  deeply  imbedded  in 
the  Vedanta  literature,  is  easily  grasped,  appears  profound, 
and  plays  entirely  into  Sankara's  hands.  It  is  easy  on  that 
account  to  argue  that  Ramanuga  was  less  than  logical  or 
thorough-going.  And  yet,  in  fact,  it  was  Sankara  who  was 
most  deeply  inconsistent,  for  he  availed  himself  constantly 
of  the  formulas  of  the  lower  knowledge,  which  on  his  view 
could  have  no  real  truth  within  them. 

To  illustrate  the  two  interpretations  and  the  appeal  which 
each  could  make  to  the  scriptures,  we  may  take  a  brief  pas 
sage  from  the  Khandogya-Upanishad :  "As  the  bees,  my  son, 
make  honey  by  collecting  the  juices  of  distant  trees,  and  re 
duce  the  juices  into  one  form,  and  these  juices  have  no  dis 
crimination,  so  that  they  might  say,  I  am  the  juice  of  this 
tree  or  that,  in  the  same  manner,  my  son,  all  these  creatures, 
when  they  have  become  merged  in  the  True  (either  in  deep 
sleep  or  death),  know  not  that  they  are  merged  in  the  True."  l 

The  direct  purpose  of  the  passage  is  to  answer  the  ques 
tion  how  it  happens  that  those  who  are  sleeping,  and  there 
fore  merged  in  the  All,  do  not  know  that  they  have  obtained 
true  Being.  But  the  answer  implies  an  ambiguity  of  inter 
pretation  familiar  to  students  of  Spinoza.  How  are  Spinoza's 
attributes  related  to  substance?  Do  they  exhibit  its  essence 
truly,  or  are  they  simply  appearances  to  the  observer?  Are 
the  juices  really  in  the  honey,  or  has  their  distinction  been 
totally  lost  in  the  unity?  The  first  interpretation  gives  qual 
ified  monism,  the  second  gives  abstract  monism,  but  each 
can  appeal  to  the  text. 

It  is  by  working  along  the  first  line  that  Ramanuga  comes 
to  the  definition  of  Brahman  as  "the  highest  Person,  who  is 
essentially  free  from  all  imperfections,  and  possesses  num 
berless  classes  of  auspicious  qualities  of  unsurpassable  ex 
cellence."  2  In  his  Commentary  he  comes  to  a  direct  reckoning 
with  the  abstractionists.  He  first  states  their  view  with  re 
markable  fairness.  He  assembles  two  pages  of  scriptural 
quotations  in  its  support,  which  seem  crushing.  He  ex- 

1  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  I,  p.  101.         *  Ibid.,  Vol.  XLVIII,  p.  4. 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  123 

pounds  also  the  basis  of  its  doctrine  of  nescience.  He  de 
velops  the  philosophical  arguments  which  lead  that  way. 
And  then  he  turns  upon  it  in  the  following  smashing  counter 
attack:  "This  entire  theory  rests  on  a  fictitious  foundation 
of  altogether  hollow  and  vicious  arguments  incapable  of 
being  stated  in  definite  logical  alternatives,  and  devised  by 
men  who  are  destitute  of  those  particular  qualities  which 
cause  individuals  to  be  chosen  by  the  Supreme  Person  re 
vealed  in  the  Upanishads;  whose  intellects  are  darkened  by 
the  impression  of  beginningless  evil;  and  who  thus  have  no 
insight  into  the  nature  of  words  and  sentences,  into  the  real 
purport  conveyed  by  them,  and  into  the  procedure  of  sound 
argumentation,  with  all  its  methods  depending  on  perception 
and  the  other  instruments  of  right  knowledge.  The  theory 
therefore  must  needs  be  rejected  by  all  those,  who,  through 
texts,  perception,  and  the  other  means  of  knowledge — 
assisted  by  sound  reasoning — have  an  insight  into  the  true 
nature  of  things."  l 

He  then  proceeds  to  argue  at  large  that  perception  in 
volves  distinction;  that  plurality,  although  not  ultimate,  is 
certainly  not  unreal;  that  there  is  no  consciousness  without 
an  object;  that  all  knowledge  involves  distinction  and  syn 
thesis.  In  short,  he  develops  the  essential  positions  of  a  con 
crete  monism  when  opposing  an  abstractionist  method.  He 
then  attends  to  the  exegesis  of  the  scriptural  texts  which  had 
been  adduced  in  favor  of  Sankara.  "We  now  turn  to  the 
numerous  texts  which,  according  to  the  view  of  our  opponent, 
negative  the  existence  of  plurality.  But  what  all  these  texts 
deny  is  only  plurality  in  so  far  as  contradicting  that  unity 
of  the  world  which  depends  on  its  being  in  its  entirety  an 
effect  of  Brahman,  and  having  Brahman  for  its  inward  ruling 
principle  and  its  true  Self.  They  do  not,  on  the  other  hand, 
deny  that  plurality  on  Brahman's  part  which  depends  on  its 
intention  to  become  manifold."  2 

In  Ramanuga's  opinion,  then,  concrete,  spiritualistic 
monism  is  the  teaching  of  the  scriptures,  but  by  no  means 
pantheism.  He  sets  aside  the  high-handed  assumption  of 

1  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  XLVIII,  p.  39.  2  Ibid.,  p.  84. 


124  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

Sankara  that  all  texts  not  pantheistic  belong  to  the  lower 
order  of  knowledge.  In  general,  Ramanuga,  like  the  Hege 
lians,  finds  a  measure  of  truth  in  the  categories  and  inter 
pretations  of  ordinary  life  and  reflection.  To  give  these  over, 
therefore,  with  Sankara,  to  utter  illusion  or  empty  symbol 
ism  is  quite  impossible. 

We  should  notice  that  the  issue  is  fought  by  Ramanuga 
on  the  basis  of  an  appeal  to  sound  logical  method,  to  com 
petent  critical  reflection,  and  to  a  fair  interpretation  of  the 
sacred  literature.  This  needs  emphasis  the  more  because 
the  regular  Brahmans  throughout  the  centuries  have  fos 
tered  the  opinion  that  Ramanuga  was  vastly  inferior  in 
point  of  thoroughness  and  logical  consistency  to  their  own 
great  leader.  When  this  opinion  is  reflected  in  the  medium 
of  a  western  scholar's  mind,  it  tends  to  take  shape  in  such 
a  passage  as  the  following:  "It  must  be  admitted  therefore 
that  in  India,  instead  of  one  Vedanta-philosophy,  we  have 
really  two,  springing  from  the  same  root  but  extending  its 
branches  in  two  very  different  directions,  that  of  Sankara 
being  kept  for  unflinching  reasoners  who,  supported  by  an 
unwavering  faith  in  Monism,  do  not  shrink  from  any  of  its 
consequences;  another,  that  of  Ramanuga,  trying  hard  to 
reconcile  their  Monism  with  the  demands  of  the  human 
heart  that  required,  and  will  always  require,  a  personal  god, 
as  the  last  cause  of  all  that  is,  and  an  eternal  soul  that  yearns 
for  an  approach  to  or  a  reunion  with  that  Being."  1 

But  this  view  should  no  longer  be  allowed  to  pass  current. 
The  issue  between  the  two  types  of  Vedanta  is  both  literary 
and  philosophical.  Dr.  Thibaut  has  made  clear  that  on  the 
literary  question  Ramanuga  is  at  least  as  well  fortified  in  his 
interpretation  of  the  scriptures  as  is  Sankara;  and  even  Max 
Miiller,  in  other  passages,  accepts  that  estimate.2  On  the 
philosophical  question  the  almost  unanimous  verdict  of 
western  thought,  I  believe,  would  ascribe  the  superior  force 
and  value  to  the  method  of  Ramanuga.  Personally  I  should 
make  only  this  reservation:  If  it  is  stipulated  that  the  Ve- 

1  Max  Miiller,  Six  Systems  of  Indian  Philosophy,  p.  252. 

2  Ibid.,  pp.  245,  247,  and  249. 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  125 

danta  is  to  stand  as  an  abstract  pantheistic  monism,  then 
of  course  we  ought  to  go  the  whole  figure  and  hold  with 
Sankara  even  to  the  extreme  of  his  esoteric  teaching.  And 
some  such  stipulation  really  seems  to  be  in  the  minds  of  those 
critics  who  think  of  the  western  Absolute  Idealism  as  Brah- 
manical  pantheism. 

II 

The  doctrine  of  appearance  developed  by  the  orthodox 
Vedanta  is  the  well  known  teaching  of  Maya,  the  veil  of 
systematic  illusion.  Appearance  is  manifold;  Brahman  is 
without  differences.  No  part,  phase,  or  aspect  of  the  order 
of  appearance,  then,  can  present  anything  that  even  in  a 
relative  degree  bodies  forth  the  real.  It  is  true  that  this 
account  of  appearance  is  contradictory.  Maya  can  no  more 
be  united  with  an  undifferentiated  Brahman  than  the 
Parmenidean  Way  of  Opinion  could  be  reconciled  with  the 
Way  of  Truth.  The  present  point,  however,  is  that  it  is 
the  only  view  that  is  even  in  any  degree  compatible  with 
Sankara's  Vedanta. 

The  interpretation  of  appearance  given  by  the  Hegelian 
form  of  idealism  is  of  course  entirely  different  from  this. 
Hegel  defends  the  power  of  human  categories  to  seize  truth, 
but  regards  such  seizure  as  a  matter  of  varying  degrees, 
depending  upon  the  adequacy  of  the  categories  employed. 
The  doctrine  of  degrees  of  reality,  professed  by  our  absolute 
idealists  throughout,  is  then  the  rejection  in  principle  of 
the  pantheistic  Vedanta.  If  the  categories  of  man's  thought 
and  experience  grasp  the  real  in  varying  degrees,  and  if 
some  estimate  may  be  formed  concerning  which  are  more 
adequate  and  which  are  less  so,  we  are  in  a  totally  different 
world  of  thought  from  that  of  the  orthodox  Brahman.  In 
fact,  we  are  in  the  thought  world  of  Aristotle  rather  than 
Sankara,  of  philosophical  theism  rather  than  of  pantheism. 

It  is  true  that,  in  the  view  of  western  idealism,  any  or 
dinary  or  finite  category  is  less  than  absolute.  It  always 
presents  a  matter  which  is  an  aspect  of  a  larger  whole  and 
is  real  only  as  upborne  by  the  larger  whole.  If,  then,  we 


126  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

use  Mr.  Bradley's  language,  we  shall  soon  be  talking  of 
such  things, — everything, — as  "mere  appearance,"  and  not 
"  reality."  Such  a  mode  of  speech  may  mislead  even  the 
very  elect  and  it  is  almost  certain  to  cause  trouble  for  prag- 
matists.  But  it  must  be  remembered  that  the  doctrine  of 
degrees  of  reality,  which  a  careful  reader  will  find  deeply  in 
volved  even  in  Mr.  Bradley's  text,  is  no  clever  device  ar 
ranged  to  save  the  idealist  from  the  charge  of  pantheism, 
but  is  rather  of  the  very  essence  of  both  the  Aristotelian 
and  the  Hegelian  modes  of  thought. 

Now  on  this  conception  of  Maya  Ramanugists,  as  is  well 
known,  oppose  the  followers  of  Sankara  all  along  the  line. 
Isvara,  the  Lord  through  whom  the  world  is  created,  is 
illusion  to  Sankara;  to  Ramanuga  this  conception  of  the 
Godhead,  as  forming  the  ground  of  the  order  of  experience, 
presents  the  "very  God  of  very  God."  Indeed,  the  material 
world  itself,  while  its  inner  truth  is  a  Universal  Self,  is  re 
garded  by  Ramanuga  as  having  a  relative  existence  expres 
sive  of  the  genuine  nature  of  things.  He  is  fond  of  speaking 
of  the  material  world,  together  with  the  souls  of  men,  as 
forming  the  "body  of  Brahman."  The  argument  against 
the  doctrine  of  Maya  pervades  Ramanuga's  Commentary. 
Plurality  and  distinction  from  Brahman,  he  urges,  although 
never  amounting  to  absolute  separation,  must  have  an  un 
deniable  recognition  in  our  world  system. 

A  recent  Hindu  writer,  after  making  explicit  acknowledg 
ment  of  his  obligations  to  Ramanuga,  sums  up  his  own  con 
clusions  in  a  way  that  splendidly  embodies  the  teaching  of 
the  ancient  sage  of  the  theistic  Vedanta:  "We  are,  therefore, 
compelled  to  admit  the  existence  of  a  material  or  objective 
world  distinct  though  inseparable  from  the  world  of  spirit. 
We  are  compelled  to  recognize  a  world  to  which  the  concep 
tions  of  space  and  time,  quality  and  quantity,  substance  and 
attribute,  cause  and  effect,  apply  in  contradistinction  from 
the  world  of  spirit,  to  which  these  conceptions  do  not  apply. 
Here  Absolute  Monism,  like  that  of  the  great  Sankara,  fails 
us.  Its  analysis  of  experience  is  halting  and  one-sided.  It 
sees  enough  to  detect  the  error  of  popular  Dualism.  It  sees 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  127 

that  Nature  is  not  independent  of  God,  that  it  has  only  a 
relative  and  not  an  absolute  existence.     This  relative  ex 
istence  it  interprets  as  non-existence.    Agreeing  with  popular 
thought  in  thinking  that  absolute  existence  is  the  only  form 
of  existence,  it  denies  existence  to  Nature  as  soon  as  it  finds 
out  that  it  has  no  absolute  existence.     Again,  sharing  in 
the  popular  mistake  that  unity  is  opposed  to  difference, — 
not  knowing  that  unity  and   difference  are  both  implied 
in  relation, — it  denies  that  Nature  is  distinct  from  God,  when 
it  sees  that  it  is  one  with  him  in  the  sense  of  being  indis- 
solubly  related  to  him.     There  is,  therefore,  to  it  only  one 
existence,  unrelated  to  any  other  existence.     The  one  ab 
solute   existence   is   above   space,   time,   quality,   quantity, 
cause  and  effect,  without  any  relation  to  anything  in  space 
and  time,  anything  admitting  of  quantity  and  quality,  any 
thing  under  the  law  of  cause  and  effect.     The  latter  order 
of  existence   is  only   appearance,   the   result  of  ignorance, 
and  has  no  relation  to  knowledge  properly  so  called.     Such 
Monism  does  not  see  that  the  Absolute,  the  Spaceless,  the 
Timeless,   the  Unchangeable,   necessarily   implies   a   world 
of  space,  time  and  change,  and  is  inconceivable  and  un 
meaning  without  the  latter.     Absolute  Monism,  therefore, 
such  as  denies  the  real  existence  of  the  world  of  time  and 
space,  has  no  place,  we  see,  in  the  Theism  that  a  correct 
analysis  of  knowledge  reveals  to  us."  ! 

This  author  recognizes  that  the  view  which  he  is  ex 
pounding  as  his  own  is  identical  with  the  Absolute  Idealism 
of  western  philosophy;  and  indeed  its  thoroughly  Hegelian 
spirit  will  be  discerned  at  once  by  all  students  of  these  sub 
jects.  But  it  is  Vedantism,  used  in  the  service  of  the  teach 
ing  of  the  Brahma  Somaj,  in  contradistinction  to  the  or 
thodox  Brahmanical  doctrine. 

Ill 

All  Vedantism  culminates,  of  course,  in  the  doctrine  of 
the  Universal  Self,  as  at  once  the  inward  life  of  all  Being  and 

1  Sitdnath  Tattvabhushan,  The  Philosophy  of  Brahmaism,  pp.  i66f. 


128  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  true  essence  of  every  finite  self.  But  the  exact  sweep 
and  meaning  of  this  doctrine,  as  consistently  interpreted  ac 
cording  to  the  viewpoint  and  method  of  the  straitest  sect 
of  the  Brahmans,  is  perhaps  too  little  appreciated  by  western 
students.  If  that  were  clearly  grasped,  we  might  hear  less 
of  the  charge  that  it  is  identical  with  the  Hegelian  concep 
tion  on  this  point. 

The  difficulty  with  our  western  appreciation  is  that  it 
is  apt  to  be  founded  upon  the  Upanishad  literature  or  other 
semi-popular  expositions.  But  such  accounts  belong,  at 
least  prevailingly,  to  what  Sankara  calls  the  lower  order  of 
knowledge.  They  are  not  really  true  at  all.  And  I  believe 
that  our  western  student  rarely  contemplates  the  genuine 
esoteric  teaching  of  Brahmanism. 

We  are  apt  to  think  that  the  finite  self  is  regarded  as  a 
part  of  Brahman.  Indeed,  one  of  the  Vedanta-sutras  de 
clares  so  in  set  terms.  Sankara,  however,  deliberately  in 
serts  into  the  text  at  this  point  the  Sanskrit  word  iva,  "as 
it  were,"  and  then  proceeds  to  explain  that,  since  the  Brah 
man  has  no  parts,  this  cannot  be  regarded  as  strictly  true. 
That  is,  it  is  a  viewpoint  belonging  to  the  lower  order  of 
knowledge  and  is  not  really  true  at  all. 

The  esoteric  doctrine,  then,  declares  that  the  finite  self 
is  the  Universal  Self,  without  restriction  or  qualification; 
"  there  is  no  difference."  It  is  not  a  genuine  concreting  or 
specifying  of  the  universal  life  to  an  individual  point  of 
view  or  center  of  personality;  it  simply  is  God  in  his  fulness, 
and  nothing  more  can  be  said.  Sankara  speaks,  to  be  sure, 
of  the  individual  soul  as  presenting  the  Universal  Self  sub 
ject  to  the  limitation  of  the  unreal  upadhis  due  to  Maya. 
But  since  Maya  is  total  illusion,  and  the  upadhis  totally 
unreal,  it  follows  that  self  and  God  are  absolutely  identical. 
There  is  no  real  discrimination  or  difference  of  viewpoint 
possible. 

Western  students  often  think  of  Brahmanism  as  teach 
ing  that  the  soul  at  the  last  will  return  to  Brahman,  "slip 
into  the  shining  sea,"  and  be  merged  and  lost  in  the  Infinite. 
Indeed,  certain  Upanishad  passages  so  declare.  But  this 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  129 

also  is  a  mode  of  speech,  a  viewpoint  of  the  lower  knowledge. 
Sankara  says:  "Some  maintain  that  the  passages  of  scrip 
ture  as  to  going  [to  the  Brahman]  refer  to  the  higher  [not  to 
the  lower,  attribute-possessing  Brahman].  This  cannot  be, 
because  a  going  to  the  Brahman  is  impossible.  For  the  all- 
present  highest  Brahman,  inmost  of  all,  who  is  the  soul 
that  is  within  all,  of  whom  it  is  said:  .  .  .  'Self  only  is 
this  universe'  .  .  .  etc., — to  this  Brahman  whose  character 
is  determined  by  passages  of  scripture  like  these,  there  can 
not  now  or  ever  be  a  going  in.  For  we  cannot  go  to  a  place 
where  we  already  are;  but  on  the  contrary,  according  to 
common  acceptation,  only  to  another  place."  l  The  great 
maxim  of  Vedantism,  "That  art  Thou,"  when  interpreted 
in  the  orthodox  manner,  also  carries  with  it  the  denial  of 
any  difference  whatever. 

Now  this  whole  doctrine  is,  of  course,  fairly  incomprehen 
sible  to  the  absolute  idealist  of  the  West.  The  point  is  not 
at  all  that  the  western  scholar  cannot  fathom  it;  one  may 
believe  that  we  do  as  well  in  this  respect  as  the  Hindu.  The 
point  is  rather  that  it  is  repugnant  to  the  entire  theory  of 
thought  and  predication  upon  which  western  idealism  rests. 
Identity  without  difference  is  a  meaningless  category,  and 
all  attempts  to  utter  the  esoteric  Brahmanical  teaching 
upon  this  subject  are  struck  with  an  inevitable  blight. 

Hegelianism  holds,  as  is  well  known,  that  the  finite  in 
dividual  is  real,  not  in  his  own  right,  but  through  the  pres 
ence  within  him  of  the  Absolute  Self.  This  Universal  Spirit, 
then,  is  the  source  and  inspiration  of  knowledge,  morals, 
religion,  and  the  entire  cultural  and  spiritual  life  of  man. 
But  here  we  are  dealing  with  a  concrete,  system-founding 
universal,  one  which  bears  up  within  its  life  the  essential 
ends  of  finite  individuality.  For  such  a  view,  even  the  nat 
uralistic  or  temporal  phases  of  the  conscious  life  of  the  in 
dividual  have  a  relative  reality  for  the  system,  and  the  full 
meaning  of  the  individual's  life,  the  completed  ideal  of  con 
creted  personality,  would  of  necessity  be  deeply  embedded 

1  Quoted  from  Deussen,  System  of  the  Vedanta^  p.  109;  see  also  Sacred 
Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  XXXVIII,  p.  394. 


130  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

in  the  nature  of  the  real.  To  the  Hegelian  it  seems  absurd, 
it  is  true,  to  attempt  to  safeguard  finite  personality  by  mak 
ing  war  upon  the  dominant  sway  of  the  Universal  Spirit; 
but  if  the  kind  of  Universal  Spirit  that  is  postulated  is  one 
that  is  interesting  itself  in  finite  individuals,  a  genuinely 
'concrete  universal,'  it  may  be  to  each  finite  self  "a  rock, 
a  fortress,  and  a  might."  So  far  as  these  phases  of  Hegelian- 
ism  are  developed,  it  would  seem  to  point  towards  a  theistic 
interpretation  of  the  meaning  of  the  world-system.  At  any 
rate,  it  affords  to  finite  individuality,  in  the  order  of  time,  a 
vastly  more  affirmative  status  than  orthodox  Brahmanism 
gives;  and  even  if  we  recognize  that  its  suggestions  of  a 
timeless  basis  of  personality  are  perhaps  crossed  by  other 
motives,  it  still  fortifies  the  essential  ends  of  human  en 
deavor  in  the  cultural  process  as  strict  Brahmanism  does 
not  even  attempt  to  do. 

When  we  turn  to  the  meditations  of  Ramanuga  on  this 
problem,  however,  we  find  ourselves  again  in  an  atmosphere 
more  congenial  to  a  western  idealist.  He  first  defends  the 
plain  natural  meaning  of  the  sutra  which  holds  that  the 
finite  self  is  part  of  Brahman.  This  is  at  best,  however,  a 
very  uninstructive  and  inadequate  conception,  and  Ra 
manuga  does  not  stop  there.  For  he  observes:  "To  hold 
that  the  individual  soul  is  a  part  of  Brahman  does  not  ex 
plain  matters;  for  by  a  'part'  we  understand  that  which 
constitutes  part  of  the  extension  of  something.  If,  then, 
the  soul  occupied  part  of  the  extension  of  Brahman,  all  its 
imperfections  would  belong  to  Brahman.  Nor  can  the  soul 
be  a  part  of  Brahman  if  we  take  'part'  to  mean  a  piece; 
for  Brahman  does  not  admit  of  being  divided  into 
pieces,  and  moreover,  the  difficulties  connected  with 
the  former  interpretation  would  present  themselves  here 
also."  1 

If  he  still  defends,  then,  the  language  of  the  sutra,  that 
the  soul  is  a  part  of  Brahman,  it  is  with  the  purpose  of  vin 
dicating  man's  genuine  membership  in  the  organic  system 
of  reality.  He  next  studies  the  relation  of  the  finite  to  the 
1  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  XLVIII,  pp. 


HEGELIANISM  AND  THE  VEDANTA  131 

Infinite,  with  the  result  of  establishing  for  the  finite  a  very 
significant  measure  of  being  for  itself.  As  Thibaut  expresses 
the  matter,  "The  individual  soul  of  Ramanuga,  on  the 
other  hand,  is  really  an  individual;  it  has  indeed  sprung 
from  Brahman,  and  is  never  outside  Brahman,  but  never 
theless  it  enjoys  a  separate  personal  existence  and  will  re 
main  a  personality  forever."  1 

The  problem  of  human  destiny  can  be  touched  only 
briefly.  Here  the  orthodox  doctrine  can  hardly  be  stated 
without  accommodation  to  the  language  of  the  lower  knowl 
edge,  but  the  teaching  of  Ramanuga  is  straightforward. 
Thibaut  summarizes  it  as  follows:  "The  release  from  the 
round  of  rebirth  means,  according  to  Sankara,  the  absolute 
merging  of  the  individual  soul  in  Brahman,  due  to  the  dis 
missal  of  the  erroneous  notion  that  the  soul  is  distinct  from 
Brahman;  according  to  Ramanuga  it  only  means  the  soul's 
passing  from  the  troubles  of  earthly  life  into  a  kind  of  heaven 
or  paradise  where  it  will  remain  forever  in  undisturbed 
personal  bliss." 

The  philosophical  idea  that  is  involved  in  Ramanuga's 
view  is  based  upon  the  logical  motives  that  pervade  his 
entire  method  and  system  of  thought.  It  happened  to  en 
gage,  however,  with  the  mythological  conception  of  Vishnu's 
heaven,  already  developed  among  the  teeming  millions  of 
the  Vishnuite  religion.  Accordingly,  the  crude  popular 
thought  of  that  sectarian  movement,  partly  theistic,  as  it 
was,  and  partly  pantheistic,  began  to  form  itself  under 
Ramanuga's  influence.  Partly  because  the  pure  philosoph 
ical  influence  could  never  largely  dominate  the  mass,  and 
partly,  one  may  judge,  because  of  certain  inadequacies  of 
his  own  thinking,  the  result  has  been  equivocal  in  many 
ways.  And  yet,  it  is  fair  to  say  that  since  his  time  the  in 
tellectual  forces  in  India  which  have  attempted  to  resist 
pantheism  while  remaining  true  to  the  Vedanta  have  owed 
most  of  their  power  to  him. 

The  charge  that  Hegelianism  is  Brahmanistic  pantheism 
is  usually  made,  we  noticed,  in  a  form  quite  loose  and  vague. 
1  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  Vol.  XXXIV,  pp.  xxxf. 


132  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

We  are  now  forced  to  conclude  that  in  what  seems  to  be  its 
substantial  meaning  the  contention  must  be  entirely  re 
pudiated.  If  the  critic  really  wishes  to  press  the  case,  he 
should  be  required  to  present  a  thoroughly  drawn  bill  of 
particulars. 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION 
G.  WATTS  CUNNINGHAM 

FROM  time  to  time  within  recent  years  the  idealist  has 
been  challenged  to  show  cause  why  his  doctrine  of  truth  as 
logical  consistency  should  not  be  drummed  out  of  camp  as 
a  wholly  vacuous,  useless,  and  even  meaningless  conception. 
"As  a  special  favor,"  Professor  Dewey  pleads,  "will  not  the 
objective  idealist  show  how,  in  some  one  single  instance,  his 
immanent  *  reason'  makes  any  difference  as  respects  the 
detection  and  elimination  of  error,  or  gives  even  the  slightest 
assistance  in  discovering  and  validating  the  truly  worth- 
ful?"  *  Dr.  Schiller,  less  prone  to  compromise,  unqualifiedly 
condemns  the  doctrine:  "The  doctrine  that  only  the  Whole 
can  be  true  is  seen  to  mean  that  humanly  nothing  can  be 
true,  and,  indeed,  to  be  ultimately  meaningless,  because  it 
construes  truth  in  such  a  way  that  it  is  no  longer  distin 
guishable  from  error."  2  Even  within  the  house  of  its 
friends  the  coherence  theory  is  not  wholly  free  from  sus 
picion.  "Whether  or  not  idealism  will  ultimately  succeed 
in  its  task,"  Professor  Bode  believes,  "the  reconciliation 
and  blending  of  the  particular  and  the  transcendental  is  at 
all  events  its  peculiar  and  pressing  obligation."  3  And  he 
is  apparently  inclined  to  think  that  the  task  cannot  be  ac 
complished,  is  indeed  a  hopeless  one,  since  the  transcendental 
element,  which  "somehow  holds  over  from  one  moment  of 
experience  to  another"  and  which  obviously  is  essential  to 
the  coherence  tljeory,  is  frankly  branded  by  him  as  a  'vicious 
abstraction.'  Likewise,  Professor  Sabine  in  his  thoroughly 
searching  and  very  suggestive  criticism  of  Bosanquet's 
Logic  raises  the  following  questions  concerning  the  theory: 

1  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XV,  1906,  p.  474. 

2  Proc.  Arist.  Soc.,  1910-1911,  p.  156. 

8  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XIX,  1910,  p.  608;  see  also  pp.  601,  604. 


134  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

"If  truth  is  the  whole,  and  if  totality  is  the  ultimate  prin 
ciple  of  individuality  and  value,  and  if  thought  is  just  the 
nisus  of  experience  toward  its  completeness,  what  is  this 
more  perfect  experience  to  which  judgment  is  not  the  key? 
Is  it  altogether  perverse  to  suspect  that  the  defect  is  not 
in  the  relational  form  of  judgment  but  in  the  coherence 
theory  of  truth?  Is  it  not  really  more  probable  that  the 
concrete  universal  is  an  inadequate  logical  principle?"  l 

Such  criticisms  as  these  strike  at  a  very  vital  spot  in  the 
idealistic  theory.  If  they  are  justified,  idealism  stands  in 
need  of  pretty  drastic  revision;  for  surely  idealism  cannot 
surrender  the  coherence  theory  and  at  the  same  time  retain 
its  traditional  form.  Can  the  idealist  satisfactorily  meet 
these  objections?  The  aim  of  the  present  paper  is  to  indi 
cate  in  outline  the  way  in  which  they  may  perhaps  be  met. 
My  excuse  for  venturing  to  discuss  a  problem  which  others 
more  competent  have  discussed  before  me, — if  an  excuse  for 
an  independent  consideration  of  a  basic  question  be  neces 
sary, — is  that  to  my  mind  something  yet  remains  to  be  said 
on  the  problem  which  has  not,  so  far  as  I  am  aware,  been 
explicitly  said.  My  thesis  is  that,  if  the  coherence  theory 
is  to  be  saved,  the  transcendental  principle  of  unity  within 
experience  upon  which  it  insists  and  which  it  calls  ' thought' 
or  'reason'  must  be  brought  definitely  into  touch  with 
the  concrete  situations  in  which  it  is  supposed  to  function 
and  must  be  so  defined  as  to  imply  an  intelligible  view  of 
the  temporal  order;  in  short,  that  coherence  must  be  so 
construed  as  to  place  the  emphasis  on  organization  of  ends 
rather  than  mere  abstract  logical  consistency. 

I 

Historically,  the  coherence  theory  had  its  origin,  I  suppose, 
in  the  obligation  which  thinkers  felt  to  meet  the  atomism  of 
Hume  and  the  utter  scepticism  implied  by  it.  On  the  basis 
of  such  a  theory  as  that  which  Hume, — logically  enough,  it 
would  seem, — reared  upon  the  premises  of  empiricism,  no 

1  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XXI,  1912,  p.  564. 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION  135 

tenable  doctrine  of  truth  could  possibly  be  constructed. 
Kant's  'transcendental  unity  of  apperception'  was  a  state 
ment  of  the  counter  theory.  Hume  places  all  of  the  em 
phasis  on  the  discontinuity  and  discreteness  among  expe 
riences;  Kant,  on  the  contrary,  directs  attention  rather  to  the 
unity  among  experiences  and  to  their  mutual  interrelations 
and  implications.  All  of  your  experiences,  Kant  says  in 
effect,  from  those  of  sensibility  to  those  of  the  understanding, 
from  sense-perception  to  scientific  insight,  have  significance 
and  meaning,  and  so  may  be  called  true  or  false,  only  as 
they  are  included  within  some  sort  of  system,  only  as  they 
are  bound  together  in  a  kind  of  network  of  relations.  And 
the  coherence  theory  as  thus  put  by  Kant  has  been,  in  prin 
ciple,  the  basis  for  all  the  later  forms  which  the  theory  has 
taken.  All  along,  then,  the  coherence  theory  has  emphasized 
system  as  the  criterion  of  meaning,  and  it  has  persistently 
insisted  that  apart  from  system  there  is  no  standard.1 

As  I  apprehend  the  matter,  this  theory  has  been  subjected 
to  attack  by  pragmatists  and  others  not  primarily  because 
it  lays  emphasis  upon  system  and  unity  within  experience, 
but  rather  because  of  the  sort  of  unity  upon  which  the  chief 
emphasis  is  laid.  According  to  the  theory,  the  unifying 
principle  is  a  kind  of  immanently  'constitutional'  and  'or 
ganizational'  reason,  a  thought-element  which  somehow 
holds  over  from  one  moment  of  experience  to  the  next,  an 
intellectual  principle  which  is  in  some  sense  'transcenden 
tal.'  But  the  critics  find  that  such  a  conception  as  this  is 
open  to  at  least  two  basic  objections.  In  the  first  place,  they 
hold,  the  unity  thus  posited  by  the  theory  is  too  far  removed 
from,  too  externally  related  to,  the  concrete  situations  in 
which  it  is  supposed  to  function;  it  is  too  much  "a  form  or 
mode  of  some  supra-empirical  ego,  mind  or  consciousness."  2 
Hence  "we  must  replace  it  by  the  doctrine  that  only  the 
relevant  can  be  true,  and  that  the  relevant  must  always  be 
relative  to  a  purpose."  3  And  in  the  second  place,  it  is  held, 
the  principle  of  unity  assumed  by  the  theory  fails  to  do  jus- 

1  Cf.  Bradley,  Essays  on  Truth  and  Reality,  Ch.  VII. 

2  Dewey,  loc.  cit.  3  Schiller,  loc.  cit. 


136  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

tice  to  the  sort  of  unity  which  is  actually  found  within  con 
crete  experience.  As  a  matter  of  indisputable  fact,  expe 
rience  grows  in  time  and  as  a  result  it  involves  a  considerable 
degree  of  discontinuity  and  hesitancy;  but  the  unity  posited 
by  the  coherence  theory  is  timeless,  and  therefore  the  theory 
fails  to  discover  any  ultimate  significance  in  the  temporal 
order.  Temporal  discreteness  seems  on  the  face  of  it  to 
have  little  to  do  with  abstract  consistency.  In  short,  the 
coherence  theory  is  incompetent  to  account  for  the  reality 
of  the  time-order  and  implies  that  ultimately  the  temporal 
must  be  transcended  as  belonging  to  an  inherently  imperfect 
type  of  experience  which  cannot  be  regarded  as  of  ultimate 
worth. 

As  regards  the  Kantian  conception  above  referred  to,  it 
seems  to  me  that  such  objections  hold  without  question.  In 
the  place  of  Hume's  atomic  chaos  Kant  substitutes  an  a  priori 
absolutism  and  calls  it  experience;  but  so  far  as  one  can  see, 
nothing  of  value  is  gained  by  substituting  one  abstraction 
for  another.  It  is  perhaps  natural  that  the  theory  in  its 
origin  should  have  taken  such  an  abstract  form,  especially 
since  the  environment  of  its  birth  was  as  it  was;  but  that  is 
no  justification  for  the  theory  in  its  abstract  form.  The  truth 
is,  the  Kantian  theory  cannot  do  service  as  a  genuinely  help 
ful  conception;  the  *  transcendental  unity  of  apperception' 
is  too  high  and  dry,  too  much  a  deus  ex  machina  forcibly 
introduced  into  the  flow  of  experience  for  the  purpose  of 
redeeming  it  from  sheer  discontinuity  and  utter  disruption. 
The  principle  here  invoked  is  wholly  outside  of  time,  sep 
arated  by  an  impassable  chasm  from  every  concrete  situa 
tion  in  experience,  and  is  as  a  result  incapable  of  performing 
the  very  function  which  is  its  only  excuse  for  being.  The 
form  which  the  coherence  theory  takes  in  the  hands  of  Kant 
must  therefore  be  surrendered;  the  pragmatists  and  tem- 
poralists  are  right  in  urging  against  it  that  it  is  an  unworkable 
hypothesis  and  that  it  does  violence  to  some  rather  obvious 
facts. 

That  the  same  objections  hold  with  equal  force  against  the 
later  forms  of  the  coherence  theory  is,  however,  not  quite  so 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION  13? 

clear.    The  development  of  the  theory  since  the  days  of  Kant 
has  changed  it  in  certain  important  respects.     It  is  a  very 
serious  mistake,  I  think,  to  put  the  so-called  neo-Hegelian 
conception  of  coherence  on  a  level  with  the  Kantian  doctrine 
and  assume  that  they  are  equally  abstract  and  vacuous. 
Certainly  it  is  true  that  Hegel  and  the  neo-Hegelians  gen 
erally  have  aimed  to  define  thought  in  terms  more  concrete 
than  Kant  was  able  to  use  and  to  bring  the  transcendental 
element  within  experience  into  more  direct  and  vital  contact 
with  the  concrete  empirical  situations  in  which  it  is  meant  to 
function,  and  they  believe  themselves  to  have  succeeded. 
Nor  can  any  one  study  Hegel's  treatment  of  rationality  as 
set  forth  in  the  Phenomenology  and  summarized  in  his  con 
ception  of  Absolute  Knowledge,  or  a  treatment  like  that 
which    Professor   Bosanquet, — to    mention   only   one    neo- 
Hegelian, — gives  us  in  his  Logic  and  his  recent  Gifford  Lec 
tures,  without  realizing  this.    And  this  fact  should  cause  us 
to  hesitate  before  lumping  together  without  distinction  all 
forms  of  the  coherence  theory  and  dealing  with  all  as  if  they 
were  in  detail  one  and  the  same,  and  as  if  a  criticism  of  one 
were  likewise  a  criticism  of  all.    The  tendency  on  the  part 
of  the  pragmatists  to  do  precisely  this  has,  as  I  grasp  the 
controversy,  rendered  much  of  their  polemic  irrelevant. 

Nevertheless,  it  undoubtedly  is  still  open  to  question 
whether  the  coherence  theory  has  yet  been  explicitly  stated 
in  such  a  way  that  it  satisfactorily  meets  all  of  the  difficulties 
which  empiricists  seem  to  find  in  it.  Particularly  does  it  seem 
true  that  the  objections  raised  by  temporalists  have  not 
sufficiently  been  taken  into  account.  Any  theory  which 
confesses  its  incompetency  to  provide  for  the  significance  of 
the  temporal  order, — as  the  coherence  theory  does,  for  ex 
ample,  in  the  hands  of  Bosanquet  and  Bradley, — would  seem 
to  come  dangerously  near  confessing  bankruptcy.  For 
surely,  if  there  is  any  one  characteristic  of  experience  as  we 
know  it  which  is  fundamental  to  it,  it  is  its  temporal  aspect; 
what  experience  would  be  without  this  aspect  no  one  can 
imagine,  because  it  is  absolutely  basic.  Bergsonism  em 
phasizes  something  which  is  fundamental,  and  no  theory  of 


138  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

truth  and  reality  can  explain  that  away  and  at  the  same  time 
expect  to  have  smooth  sailing.  I  believe  that  the  coherence 
theory  can  satisfactorily  meet  the  objections  of  the  pragma- 
tists  and  temporalists,  but  in  order  to  do  so  the  systematic 
unity  of  experience  upon  which  it  insists  must  in  certain 
respects  be  re-stated;  at  least  the  locus  of  emphasis  must  be 
shifted.  What  is  needed  seems  to  be  not  a  denial  of  system, 
but  a  definition  of  system  in  terms  of  organization  of  ends. 
The  exponents  of  the  view  have  hitherto  placed  the  emphasis 
too  much  upon  logical  consistency;  and  the  result  of  this 
has  been  to  produce  in  them  a  bias  which  has  caused  them 
to  neglect  to  take  account  of  the  full  significance  of  the  fact 
that,  by  the  implication  of  their  own  views,  logical  consist 
ency  is  something  which  cannot  be  defined  in  the  abstract 
and  without  direct  reference  to  specific  situations.1 


II 

It  is  not  my  purpose  to  enter  here  into  a  discussion  of  the 
merits  of  the  coherence  theory.  Space  will  not  permit  this, 
and  in  this  paper  my  interest  lies  in  another  direction.  I 
will  presume,  however,  to  state  dogmatically  my  conviction 
that  it  is  useless  to  talk  of  a  theory  of  truth  and  error  apart 
from  the  assumption  of  some  sort  of  unity  within  experi 
ence.  Presumably  we  have  outgrown  the  old  correspondence 

1  "When  we  say  that  logical  consistency  is  the  end  and  criterion  of 
truth,  we  must  give  these  terms  a  broader  and  more  inclusive  meaning 
than  that  which  is  often  ascribed  to  them."  Professor  Creighton,  "The 
Nature  and  Criterion  of  Truth,"  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XVII,  1908, 
p.  602.  Professor  Creighton  has  frequently  urged  the  necessity  of  this; 
see  particularly  his  articles,  "Purpose  as  Logical  Category,"  Philosophi 
cal  Review,  Vol.  XIII,  1904,  p.  284,  and  "The  Copernican  Revolution  in 
Philosophy,"  ibid.,  Vol.  XXII,  1913,  p.  133.  As  I  suppose,  the  later 
form  of  Professor  Royce's  philosophy  tends  more  and  more  to  a  recogni 
tion  of  the  same  point.  The  changing  emphasis  of  his  views  he  himself 
notes  in  the  preface  to  his  GifFord  Lectures,  The  World  and  the  Individual, 
while  in  the  second  volume  of  The  Problem  of  Christianity  he  presents 
what  Professor  Howison  is  inclined  to  call  a  new, — new,  that  is,  for  Profes 
sor  Royce, — theory  of  knowledge. 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION  139 

theory,  and  there  is  no  possibility  of  discovering  either  truth 
or  error  in  such  a  mere  string  or  succession  of  experiences  as 
Hume  would  have  us  accept.  To  my  mind  truth  is  a  value, 
and  as  a  value  it  implies  a  standard.  Furthermore,  truth 
is  a  peculiar  sort  of  value,  —  a  value  which,  like  goodness, 
requires  a  system  in  which  to  exist.  Everything  which  is 
agreeable  to  the  palate  is  pleasurable  whether  it  is  nutritious 
or  the  reverse;  but  not  everything  which  we  believe,  indeed, 
not  everything  which  we  desire  to  believe  and  which  we 
might  perhaps  be  better  off  for  believing,  is  on  that  account 
true.  Truth  is  the  expression  of  system;  within  the  expe 
rience  of  which  truth  and  error  are  in  any  intelligible  sense 
predicable  there  must  be  some  degree  of  unity.  So  much 
seems  to  me  obvious.  "There  is  meaning  and  rationality, 
law  and  unity  in  the  mental  life  because  we  find  them 
there;"  l  if  we  did  not  find  them  there,  I  do  not  see  how  we 
could  intelligibly  define  truth.  Furthermore,  I  am  at  a  loss 
to  know  how  to  define  this  unity  except  in  terms  of  thought 
or  reason.  There  is  no  other  feature  of  experience  which 
could  serve  as  the  principle  of  such  organization  as  we 
seem  to  find  there.  To  call  the  principle  'life'  or  '  interest' 
does  not  help  us  much  unless  we  state  what  precisely  such 
terms  are  to  be  taken  to  mean;  and  when  we  attempt  to 
define  them  we  are  ultimately  driven  back  to  rationality. 
At  least  so  it  seems  to  me.  And  consequently  I  am  compelled 
to  hold  that  some  form  of  the  coherence  theory  of  truth  is 
the  only  test  of  truth  which  we  either  have  or  need.  And 
having  said  so  much  I  will  now  pass  on  to  Jthe  main  issue. 
If  we  assume^that  coherence  is  our 


,by_  coherence  ?  Can  the  doctrine 
that  *  truth  is  the  whole'  be  so  interpreted  as  to  meet  the 
criticisms  which  we  have  noted  above?  I  think  so.  But  in 
order  thus  to  define  it,  there  are  certain  basic  features  of 
thought  which  must  be  explicitly  recognized  and  insisted 
upon  and  the  implication  of  which  must  be  set  in  bold  relief. 
In  the  space  at  my  disposal  here  I  can  only  refer  to,  and 

1  MacDougall,  "The  Self  and  Mental  Phenomena,"  Psychological  Re 
view,  Vol.  XXIII,  1916,  p.  7. 


140  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

briefly  attempt  to  justify,  four  which  seem  to  be  funda 
mental. 

In  the  first  place,  thought  must  be  explicitly  defined  as 
the  principle  within  experience  which  includes  the  various 
so-called  states  of  consciousness,  both  cognitive  and  emo 
tional.  It  cannot  be  regarded  as  something  radically  and 
fundamentally  different  from  perception,  conception,  mem 
ory,  imagination,  feeling,  purpose,  interest,  and  ideals;  on 
the  contrary,  it  must  be  conceived  as  manifesting  itself 
precisely  in  and  through  these.  It  is  not  to  be  looked  upon 
as  an  event  over  against  these  experiences,  but  as  the  prin 
ciple  which  penetrates  them  and  links  them  into  a  unitary 
whole.  In  short,  it  must  be  unequivocally  identified  with 
that  principle  of  organization  by  means  of  which  the  various 
experiences  of  the  individual  may  be  said  to  belong  to  one 
and  the  same  experience.  This  seems  to  be  the  first  point 
on  which  the  coherence  theory  must  insist  if  it  is  to  stand. 

I  am,  of  course,  well  aware  that  all  of  this  will  prove  to 
be  a  very  hard  saying  indeed  in  this  day  when  i behaviorism' 
and  the  new  realism  are  contending  that  consciousness, 
even  in  the  modest  form  of  an  inoffensive  sort  of  'aware 
ness/  shall  not  retain  its  place  in  the  sun.  It  requires  some 
temerity  to  suggest  not  only  that  consciousness  must  be 
supposed  to  exist,  but  that  it  must  be  supposed  to  exist  as 
a  full-fledged  and  militant  principle  of  organization  within 
the  various  data  which  constitute  its  content.  However, 
I  do  not  see  how  the  coherence  theory  of  truth, — and  it  is 
the  fortune  of  that  theory  we  are  here  chiefly  interested 
in, — can  maintain  itself  without  making  precisely  this  asser 
tion.  Unless  it  is  willing  to  go  back  to  Kant's  abstract 
'transcendental'  element,  it  cannot  afford  to  separate 
thought  and  its  manifestations;  and,  on  the  other  hand, 
unless  the  theory  digs  the  ground  from  under  its  own  feet, 
it  cannot  deny  connectedness  among  these  data.  Nor  can 
I  discover  that  the  assertion  thus  forced  upon  the  coherence 
theory  is  without  justification  on  the  basis  of  the  facts;  on 
the  contrary,  there  seems  to  be  ample  warrant  for  it.  Un 
questionably  there  is  some  reality  corresponding  to  what 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION  141 

has  hitherto  been  called  consciousness,  and  this  reality  is 
not  a  bare  string  of  wholly  disconnected  and  unrelated  dis 
cretes.  "Unity  is  an  immediate  and  indefeasible  reality 
of  our  experience.  It  is  a  fact, — if  that  of  which  one  is  thus 
immediately  aware  can  be  called  a  fact, — whose  existence 
is  neither  posited  nor  inferred,  but  intuited."  *  At  least  it 
is  certain  that  within  any  given  pulse  of  attention,  or  within 
that  sort  of  complex  which  we  used  to  designate  as  a  pulse 
of  attention,  there  is  unity,  even  if  it  consists  in  nothing 
more  than  preference  of  one  datum  over  others.  And  where 
there  is  unity  some  principle  of  connection  must  be  func 
tioning,  nor  can  I  see  how  else  that  principle  can  satisfac 
torily  be  described  except  as  judgment. 

In  the  second  place,  if  the  coherence  theory  is  to  stand, 
thought  must  be  interpreted  by  it  as  just  that  element  which 
holds  over  from  one  moment  of  experience  to  another.  Past, 
present,  and  future  must  be  regarded  as  three  aspects  or 
phases  of  its  total  content.  It  cannot  be  conceived  as  a 
mere  psychological  event  happening  at  a  given  moment  and 
dying  with  it;  it  belongs  to  no  single  moment  as  an  isolated 
part  of  the  temporal  flux.  It  is  a  principle  rather  than  an 
event  and  its  very  nature  is  to  be  past,  present,  and  future 
at  once;  it  exists  only  in  this  tripartite  manner.  Such  a  posi 
tion  would  seem  to  be  essential  to  the  coherence  theory. 

Just  here  we  are  face  to  face  with  the  pragmatist's  execra 
tion  of  the  'transcendental.'  If  thought  is  defined  in  this 
way,  is  it  not  abstracted  from  the  concrete  flow  of  experi 
ence  and  given  a  mysterious  and  equivocal  character?  How 
can  thought  function  in  a  concrete  situation  if  by  hypothesis 
it  cannot  be  identified  with  any  given  situation,  cannot  even 
be  regarded  as  an  element  within  such  a  situation?  The 
complete  answer  to  this  question  will  concern  us  later.  For 
the  present  what  I  wish  to  say  is  that,  if  the  coherence  theory 
is  to  hold  its  own,  it  seems  to  be  reduced  to  the  necessity  of 
contending  that  thought  is,  in  the  sense  above  defined, 
'transcendental/  For  unless  thought  in  some  genuine  sense 
overarches  time,  it  is  incompetent  to  bring  the  moments 
1  MacDougall,  he.  cit. 


142  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

of  the  time-order  into  vital  contact  with  each  other  and 
consequently  is  incompetent  to  introduce  continuity  into 
the  flux  of  experience.  And  once  again,  I  cannot  see  but 
that  such  a  position  is  well  taken.  Every  normal  individual 
acts,  he  acts  in  the  light  of  ends,  and  these  ends  are  to  some 
extent  and  in  some  manner  an  expression  of  the  individual's 
past  history.  It  is  in  this  way  that  character  is  built  and 
knowledge  grows,  and  it  is  after  this  fashion  that  each  one 
is  the  architect  of  his  own  fortune.  Within  such  a  tripartite 
experience  there  must  be  some  organizing  principle  which 
is  neither  wholly  past  nor  wholly  present  nor  wholly  future, 
but  in  some  real  sense  is  all  at  once.  To  deny  such  a  prin 
ciple  is  to  deny  such  an  experience,  and  to  deny  such  an 
experience  is  to  make  inscrutable  intellectual  achievement 
and  to  nullify  the  whole  process  of  character-building.  What 
this  principle  can  be  other  than  judgment  it  is  not  easy  to 
see;  certainly  it  seems  true  that  thought  is  the  characteris 
tic  of  mind  most  nearly  adequate  to  perform  such  a  func 
tion.  And  if  the  principle  is  there  and  is  of  the  nature 
described,  then  there  is  no  great  objection  to  dubbing  it 
'  transcendental,'  if  by  the  term  is  meant  just  such  a  principle; 
obviously,  the  'transcendental'  in  this  meaning  of  the  term 
is  neither  mysterious  nor  abstract. 

In  the  third,  place,  thought  must  be  explicitly  defined  as 
a  process  of  experimentation,  trial  and  error,  essentially 
temporal  in  its  nature.  Nor  is  this  inconsistent  with  the 
characteristic  just  discussed;  on  the  contrary,  it  would 
seem  to  be  implied  by  it.  Just  because  thought  is  inclusive 
of  several  moments  of  the  temporal  series,  it  cannot  be  said 
to  belong  to  any  one  moment;  precisely  because  it  somehow 
overlaps  past,  present,  and  future,  it  can  never  be  just  past 
or  present  in  its  totality;  in  other  words,  thought  by  its  very 
nature  cannot  be  static.  Since  it  is  the  principle  of  organiza 
tion  within  the  flow  of  experience,  it  must  ipso  facto  be 
dynamic  and  evolving.  The  coherence  theory  must  em 
phasize  this  point  more  unhesitatingly  than  it  at  times 
seems  inclined  to  do;  it  must  take  seriously  its  contention 
that  thought  is  a  principle,  not  an  event  or  'state'  of  con- 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION  143 

sciousness,  and  it  must  not  hesitate  to  draw  the  conclusion 
which  this  doctrine  implies;  otherwise,  the  theory  will  tend 
more  and  more  to  separate  sharply  meaning  and  time  and 
to  deny  the  real  value  of  the  temporal  order. 

That  the  coherence  theory  minimizes,  if  it  does  not  com- 
pletely  deny,  the  significance  of  time  is  in  the  minds  of  many 
exponents  of  the  theory  no  very  serious  objection  to  it. 
With  such  an  opinion,  however,  one  cannot  unhesitatingly 
agree.  Because  time  seems  to  be  so  fundamental  in  our 
experience,  the  theory  which  involves  the  necessity  of  re 
ducing  time  to  mere  appearance  gives  us  pause;  such  an 
implication  is  at  least  sufficient  to  establish  a  strong  pre 
sumption  that  the  theory  is  somehow  poorly  conceived. 
In  any  event,  truth  as  we  know  it  and  must  define  it  con 
cerns  present  concrete  experience,  and  such  experience  is 
without  doubt  shot  through  and  through  with  time.  And 
any  definition  of  truth  which  is  to  hold  its  own  cannot 
afford  to  overlook  the  apparent  discreteness  and  discon 
tinuity  that  are  found  there.  Furthermore,  one  is  at  a  loss 
to  see  how,  if  thought  is  defined  as  suggested  above,  it  can 
be  regarded  as  other  than  temporal  in  its  nature.  If  it 
manifests  itself  in  the  various  states  of  consciousness  as  the 
principle  through  which  they  secure  that  degree  of  organiza 
tion  which  they  do  actually  possess,  and  if  this  'manifesta 
tion'  of  thought  is  taken  in  a  sense  sufficiently  concrete  to 
escape  the  sting  of  the  pragmatist's  unrelenting  opposition 
to  the  '  transcendental/  then  to  my  mind  the  criterion  of 
truth  as  logical  consistency  turns  out  to  be  a  progressive 
co-ordination  of  ends;  that  is,  the  criterion  falls  once  for  all 
within  the  temporal  stream.1 

In  the  fourth  place,  and  finally,  the  coherence  theory 
must  go  the  length  of  saying  that  thought  is  in  a  very  real 
sense  objective.  That  is  to  say,  the  proponents  of  the 

1  "That  what  is  ultimately  real — the  Absolute — must  be  beyond  time 
and  change  and  process,  present  all  at  once,  does  not  seem  to  be  a  genuine 
requirement  of  our  thought,  but  only  a  consequence  of  a  system  of  logic 
from  whose  authority  we  find  it  difficult  to  free  ourselves."  Professor 
Creighton,  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XXII,  1913,  p.  143,  note. 


144  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

theory  must  insistently  urge  that  thought  is  not  a  mere 
conscious  state  existent  within  some  particular  psychological 
history,  not  even  the  organizing  principle  of  such  an  isolated 
experience  taken  in  its  isolation.  They  must  rather  contend 
that  thought  is  to  be  found  chiefly  in  the  physical  and  social 
orders,  in  the  world-process  itself.  Of  course,  they  cannot 
deny,  there  is  no  reason  why  they  should  care  to  deny,  that 
thought  exists  in  psychological  experience;  but  there  they 
must  regard  it  as  something  gradually  to  be  attained,  as 
an  acquisition  and  not  an  endowment,  a  progressive  process 
of  creative  effort  which  matures  only  through  contact 
with  the  objective  order  and  which  becomes  aware  of  its 
j  own  fundamental  nature  through  its  unfolding.  In  short, 
^P'  thought  must  be  said  to  have  its  habitat  primarily  in  the 
objective  order  and  only  secondarily  in  the  individual. 

Any  such  position  as  this,  however,  will  inevitably  be  an 
object  of  vigorous  attack.  If  this  territory  is  definitely 
occupied,  all  the  heavy  artillery  of  the  enemies  of  the  '  supra- 
empirical'  and  '  supra-psychological '  will  begin  at  once  to 
thunder.  If  the  coherence  theory  gives  explicit  or  implicit 
recognition  to  any  such  trans-experiential  principle  as  is 
suggested  here,  does  it  not  thereby  confess  its  own  bank 
ruptcy  and  justify  its  opponents'  contention  that  it  should 
forthwith  and  forever  be  consigned  to  the  outer  darkness 
of  by-gone  superstitions?  In  answer  there  are  at  least  two 
things  which  ought  to  be  said.  The  first  of  these  is  that  any 
theory  of  truth  which  is  worth  considering  must  base  its 
claims  on  some  principle  which  in  a  very  genuine  sense 
transcends  the  limits  of  purely  individual  or  psychological 
experience.  If  there  is  any  one  lesson  which  the  history  of 
philosophical  inquiry  from  the  time  of  the  Sophists  down  to 
the  present  has  taught  us  with  unmistakable  certainty, 
I  should  hold  that  lesson  to  be  that  a  theory  of  truth  which 
seeks  its  criterion  in  merely  subjective  experience  ends  at 
last  in  giving  us  no  criterion  at  all.  The  basic  difficulty  which 
most  of  its  critics  have  found  in  the  pragmatic  test  itself 
is  that  it  narrows  its  horizon  to  the  subjective  and  conse 
quently  offers  us  no  satisfactory  and  efficient  standard;  and 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION  145 

in  every  case  the  pragmatist  feels  it  incumbent  upon  him 
self  to  point  out  that  this  is  a  mistaken  interpretation  of  what 
he  really  means.  Whatever  may  be  the  objections  to  the 
so-called  ' supra-psychological'  and  however  great  may  be 
the  obstacles  to  occupying  this  'no  man's  land,'  the  fact 
yet  remains  that  the  standard  of  truth  exists  there  or  no 
where;  we, — all  of  us,  pragmatists  and  idealists  alike,— 
find  our  standard  there  or  we  fail  in  our  quest.  But  are  the 
obstacles  involved  in  the  occupancy  of  this  territory  real 
or  imaginary?  Do  we  have  to  leap  over  insuperable  barriers 
to  get  there  ?  This  brings  me  to  the  second  point  I  desire  here 
to  make.  So  far  as  the  various  'states'  of  consciousness  are 
concerned,  it  seems  we  must  admit  at  once  that  they  exist 
nowhere  outside  of  a  psychological  experience;  certainly 
this  would  appear  to  be  true  of  all  feelings,  of  memory  and 
imagination,  and  of  pure  intuition,  if  there  be  such.  But  it 
hardly  seems  to  be  true  in  the  same  sense  of  rationality. 
Of  course,  no  one  can  dispute  the  truth  of  the  statement 
that  my  reason  exists  in  my  own  individual  mind;  this  fact 
undoubtedly  has  metaphysical  implications  of  far-reaching 
importance.  But  it  would  seem  to  be  equally  true  that  my 
reason  transcends  my  experiential  limitations.  In  order  to 
identify  ourselves  with  objective  rationality  there  is  no 
obligation  imposed  upon  us  to  lift  ourselves  by  our  own  boot 
straps;  to  be  rational  is  just  to  be  thus  identified  with  the 
objective  order  of  the  universe.  Surely  science  exists  in  no 
man's  mind;  but  surely,  also,  every  lowest  son  of  Adam  is 
in  some  sense  capable  of  science.  If  reason  were  not  'supra- 
psychological,'  the  whole  history  of  scientific  achievement 
were  utterly  inscrutable,  and,  for  that  matter,  the  whole 
history  of  society  and  even  of  the  individual  himself.  I 
have  not  space  here  to  enter  further  into  these  matters;  but 
I  do  not  see  how  we  can  afford  to  deny,  or  why  there  should 
be  any  advantage  in  denying,  what  would  seem  to  be  an 
evident  aspect  of  rationality,  namely,  that  it  is  in  a  very 
intelligible  sense  more  than  merely  psychological  in  its 
nature  and  function. 

What  I  have  been  attempting  to  say  in  this  section  may  be 


146  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

summarized  in  some  such  way  as  the  following.  Thought, 
upon  which  the  coherence  theory  lays  so  much  emphasis, 
must  not  be  supposed  to  be  an  abstract  principle,  standing 
over  against  the  various  states  of  consciousness  which  it 
somehow  mechanically  and  mysteriously  binds  together 
into  a  unity;  nor,  on  the  other  hand,  must  it  be  identified 
with  these  states.  Rather  must  it  be  conceived  as  the  prin 
ciple  of  organization  through  which  these  states  exist  as 
they  do  exist  and  which,  because  it  is  a  principle,  is  more  than 
these  states  taken  either  distributively  or  collectively.  Once 
again,  because  it  is  a  principle  of  organization  within  expe 
rience,  it  must  hold  over  from  one  moment  to  another;  on 
the  other  hand,  it  is  not  non-temporal  and  cannot  be  so  con 
ceived,  since  organization  ipso  facto  involves  time.  To  speak 
of  a  timeless  act  of  thought,  as  Green  does,  is  a  contradiction 
in  terms,  if  thought  is  taken  in  the  sense  here  insisted  upon. 
Finally,  thought  is  not  a  process  which  is  confined  wholly  to 
an  individual  biography,  as  is  a  feeling  of  pleasure  or  a  par 
ticular  desire;  thought  is  rather  the  principle  of  objectivity 
which  spans  the  gulf  between  the  individual  and  the  world. 
All  of  these  points  perhaps  have  been  made  at  one  time  or 
another  by  the  adherents  of  the  coherence  theory;  I  am  sure 
that  some  of  them  have  elsewhere  found  expression  in  un 
mistakable  terms.  But  they  are  points  which  more  often 
than  otherwise  are  ignored  by  the  critics  of  idealism,  and 
some  of  them  even  idealists  themselves  seem  to  my  mind  too 
prone  to  neglect.  This  is  the  excuse  which  I  plead  for  having 
stated  them  once  again;  and  if  this  brief  account  serves  even 
to  direct  attention  to  them  and  to  suggest  their  basic  im 
portance  for  the  coherence  theory,  it  will  not  have  failed  of 
its  purpose. 

Ill 

We  are  now  in  a  position  to  inquire  how  the  coherence 
theory  may  meet  the  two  objections  with  which  we  began. 
Since  these  objections  are  basic  and  are  the  ones  most  fre 
quently  pressed,  it  may  be  assumed  that  others  would 
hardly  prove  to  be  more  formidable.  Our  discussion  of  them 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION  147 

must  necessarily  be  very  brief,  but  the  analysis  of  the  pre 
ceding  section  is  perhaps  sufficiently  extended  to  suggest 
the  lines  along  which  a  more  elaborate  discussion  might  pro 
ceed. 

As  regards  the  first  objection,  namely,  that  the  coherence 
theory  is  too  abstract  to  be  of  service  in  the  detection  and 
elimination  of  error  and  in  the  determination  of  truth,  the 
answer  must  be  that  it  does  not  hold  of  coherence  as  organiza 
tion.  Rational  organization  is  in  no  sense  abstract  and  it 
can  only  verbally  be  separated  from  the  concrete  situation. 
For  organization  is  precisely  the  determination  of  the  more 
and  the  less  worthful  within  a  given  set  of  circumstances. 
The  doctrine  that  'the  truth  is  the  whole'  means  nothing 
more  than  that,  under  the  conditions  as  they  are  discovered 
to  be,  the  true  is  just  that  which  meets  the  demand  of  expe 
rience  for  rational  unity. 

The  pragmatist  lays  a  great  deal  of  emphasis,  and  rightly, 
upon  the  importance  of  the  concrete  problem  which  thought 
has  to  solve;  and  he  defines  truth  in  terms  of  that  which  is 
relevant  to  the  problem  in  hand.  And  all  of  this,  he  is 
apparently  inclined  to  think,  is  precluded  from  the  coherence 
theory  by  the  very  nature  of  the  theory  itself.  Such  an 
assumption,  however,  is  unjustifiable,  if  by  coherence  is 
meant  organization.  With  the  pragmatist's  assertions  that 
'only  the  relevant  is  true'  and  that  'the  relevant  is  relative 
to  a  purpose'  the  coherence  theory  is  in  complete  agreement. 
But  it  does  not  stop  here.  It  goes  further  and  offers  a  stand 
ard  by  which  the  varying  degrees  of  '  relevancy,'  as  well  as  the 
origin  of  the  purpose  through  which  the  relevant  has  a  mean 
ing,  may  be  determined.  It  is  precisely  because  the  prag 
matist  fails  to  do  this  that  the  idealist  finds  his  theory  of 
truth  wanting  in  definiteness  and  finality.  In  order  to  supply 
this  deficiency  in  the  pragmatic  method,  the  idealist  feels 
that  he  must  carry  his  quest  for  the  goal  beyond  mere 
isolated,  and  therefore  logically  valueless,  desires  and  in 
terests;  and  he  finds  no  place  to  rest  short  of  the  conception 
of  a  'whole,'  the  organization  of  desires  and  interests.  In 
short,  coherence  as  organization  lays  as  much  emphasis  as 


148  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

pragmatism  upon  the  problem  which  thought  has  to  solve, 
and  at  the  same  time  does  not  leave  the  question  of  the 
problem  itself  an  unintelligible  mystery.  Thus,  in  answer  to 
the  pragmatist's  challenge  that  the  idealist  show  how  his 
theory  of  coherence  aids  in  the  detection  and  elimination  of 
error  and  in  the  definition  of  truth,  the  idealist  may  justly 
say:  The  coherence  theory  aids  in  this  enterprise  by  explain 
ing  how  it  is  possible  for  intellectual  problems  to  emerge 
within  experience  and  how  what  is  relevant  to  the  solution 
of  those  problems  can  be  determined. 

Nor  does  the  coherence  theory  necessarily  reduce  all 
problems  to  one  kind,  namely,  logical  contradiction.  It 
would  perhaps  do  this,  provided  the  reason  ' immanent' 
within  experience  were  defined  entirely  in  isolation  from  the 
concrete  situations  in  which  it  functions.  But  to  give  such 
an  abstract  definition  of  reason  is  just  what  the  organiza 
tional  theory  refuses  to  do  Reason  must  be  conceived  con 
cretely  as  the  organizing  principle  within  the  total  situation 
or  it  is  incorrectly  conceived.l  Hence  the  rational  cannot 
be  reduced  to  terms  of  mere  abstract  contradiction,  nor  can 
all  intellectual  problems  be  regarded  as  aspects  of  such  con 
tradiction.  "For  the  thought  which  has  become  expert  in 
this  world,  such  media  as  sound,  colour,  form,  rhythm,  and 
metre  have  undoubtedly  a  logic  and  a  necessity  of  their 
own.  .  .  .  The  rhythm  that  completes  a  rhythm,  the  sound 
that  with  other  sounds  satisfies  the  educated  ear,  the  colour 
that  is  demanded  by  a  colour-scheme,  are  I  take  it  as  nec 
essary  and  as  rational  as  the  conclusion  of  a  syllogism."  l 
And  the  same  may  be  said  of  interests,  purposes,  and  feelings 
in  so  far  as  these  are  components  of  an  organizational  com 
plex;  they  have  a  necessity,  a  rationality  of  their  own.  This, 
as  I  understand  it,  is  precisely  the  position  which  the  coher 
ence  theory  is  compelled  to  take.  And  from  this  point  of 
view  intellectual  problems  may  be  as  varied  as  you  please 
and  any  particular  problem  may  be  as  novel  and  unique  as 
experience  can  furnish. 

The  second  objection, — that  the  unity  implied  by  the 
1  Bosanquet,  The  Principle  of  Individuality  and  Value,  p.  62. 


COHERENCE  AS  ORGANIZATION  149 

coherence  theory  is  not  the  sort  of  unity  found  within  actual 
experience, — is  to  my  mind  an  objection  which  holds  against 
the  theory  as  generally  conceived.  For  the  coherence  theory 
has  tended  to  exaggerate  the  continuity  of  experience  and 
to  minimize  the  obvious  discontinuity  and  disruption  which 
are  found  there.  It  finds  difficulty  in  satisfactorily  dealing 
with  the  novel  in  experience  and  in  giving  due  weight  to  the 
significance  of  the  fact  of  selective  attention.  The  supporters 
of  the  theory  have  not  infrequently  ended  by  insisting  that 
selective  attention  is  characteristic  of  an  essentially  imper 
fect  type  of  experience,  that  teleology  is  an  inadequate 
category,  and  that  the  novel  is  in  the  last  analysis  unintel 
ligible, — in  short,  that,  the  real  is  timeless  and  the  temporal 
order  is  mere  appearance.  Indeed,  this  conclusion  is  so  gen 
erally  held  by  idealists  that  it  has  usually  been  taken  as  an 
inevitable  implication  of  the  coherence  theory,  an  implica 
tion  which  the  critics  regard  as  fatal. 

However,  I  cannot  but  feel  that  if  coherence  is  in  dead 
earnest  identified  with  organization,  the  situation  must  be 
differently  viewed.  For,  in  the  first  place,  organization  im 
plies  discontinuity  and  hesitancy,  selection  and  evaluation; 
apart  from  these  organization  is  impossible.  If  there  were 
an  experience  in  which  disruption  and  selection  did  not 
occur,  it  would  be  an  experience  of  which  organization  could 
in  no  intelligible  sense,  in  no  sense  comprehensible  to  us,  be 
predicated.  Out  of  selection,  and  out  of  selection  alone, 
comes  organization.  But  selection  is  by  implication  a  proc 
ess.  And  this  leads  me  to  remark,  in  the  second  place,  that 
organization  is  by  its  very  nature  expressible  only  in  time. 
If  there  were  a  timeless  experience,  an  experience  which 
knows  no  leanings  and  possesses  no  will,  it  also  would  be  an 
experience  of  which  organization  could  in  no  intelligible 
sense  be  predicated.  Organization  is  in  its  very  essence 
dynamic  and  could  not  characterize  that  which  by  hypoth 
esis  is  static. 

From  these  considerations  two  conclusions  seem  to  me  to 
follow.  The  first  is  that,  so  far  as  concrete  human  experience 
is  concerned,  coherence  as  organization  satisfactorily  meets 


ISO  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

all  of  the  relevant  facts.  It  is  certain  that  disruption  and 
selection  are  no  obstacles  in  the  way  of  its  acceptance;  on 
the  contrary,  one  finds  it  impossible  to  imagine  what  or 
ganization  could  possibly  mean  apart  from  them.  Selective 
evaluation  and  the  progressive  introduction  of  continuity 
within  discontinuity  is  precisely  what  we  mean  by  organiza 
tion.  The  second  conclusion  is  that,  if  coherence  is  identified 
with  organization,  then  it  is  inconsistent  to  hold  that  the 
coherence  theory  of  truth  saddles  us  with  a  block  universe 
and  a  timeless  Absolute.  From  this  point  of  view  the  only 
intelligible  definition  of  reality  which  can  be  given  is  that 
it  is  a  purposive,  selective,  volitional  process;  and  such  an 
assertion  as  Professor  Bosanquet's,  that  "it  seems  unintel 
ligible  for  the  Absolute  or  for  any  perfect  experience  to  be  a 
will  or  purpose,"  1  appears  to  be  wholly  without  justification. 
The  truth  is  that  a  perfect  experience  defined  in  terms  other 
than  those  having  a  temporal  reference  is  to  us  incomprehen 
sible;  the  temporal  alone  is  intelligible.  This  implication  of 
the  organizational  theory  undoubtedly  leads  us  into  new 
difficulties.  But  whatever  these  difficulties  may  prove  to  be 
and  however  formidable  they  may  appear,  it  is  better  for  us 
to  accept  them  and  resolutely  grapple  with  them  than  to 
minimize  and  ultimately  deny  the  significance  of  some  of  the 
obvious  facts  of  experience.  For  the  alternative  confronting 
us  really  seems  to  be  this:  either  the  organizational  theory, 
accepted  with  explicit  avowal  of  its  implications  concerning 
the  ontological  value  of  time,  or  the  admission  of  the  final 
bankruptcy  of  the  concept  of  a  'world.' 

I0p.  cit.,  p.  393. 


TIME  AND  THE  LOGIC  OF  MONISTIC  IDEALISM 
JOSEPH  ALEXANDER  LEIGHTON 

I  UNDERSTAND  by  monistic  idealism  the  philosophical 
standpoint  common  to  Hegel,  Bradley,  Bosanquet,  and 
Royce  (in  his  earlier  writings,  including  The  World  and  the 
Individual).  It  identifies  the  characteristic  features  of  truth 
and  reality,  to  the  extent  of  holding  that  the  standard  is  the 
same  for  both.  Systematic  coherence,  harmonious  organiza 
tion,  the  wholeness  of  a  cosmic  individuality  which  takes  up 
into  itself  and  transforms  into  constituent  factors  in  one 
perfect  totality  all  lesser  degrees  of  individuality, — these 
are  various  ways  of  stating  the  absolute  standard  of  truth 
and  reality.  Nothing  is  real  in  isolation  or  in  independence 
of  anything  else.  The  reality  of  any  thing,  person,  or  event 
is  determined  by  its  degree  of  organization,  of  individuality, 
as  a  constituent  factor  in  the  absolute  and  perfect  totality 
of  being.  So  also  with  the  system  of  truth.  No  single  judg 
ment  is  true  out  of  relation  to  all  other  judgments.  Truth 
is  a  coherent  organization  in  the  all-inclusive  whole,  a  super- 
organic  system  of  truth.  Truth,  like  reality,  is  a  systematic 
individuality.  Some  sub-systems  of  judgments  are  truer  than 
others,  because  the  former  have  more  systematic  coherence, 
more  organization,  more  individuality;  that  is  because  they 
have  at  once  more  sweep  of  import  and  more  internal  har 
mony  of  texture. 

That  coherence  or  freedom  from  contradiction  in  a  system, 
membership  in  an  organized  totality  of  experience,  is  a  valid 
criterion  of  truth  I  do  not  question.  I  am  prepared  to  main 
tain  that  the  harmonious  organization  of  experience  into  a 
reflectively  apprehended  and  coherent  totality  of  insight,  in 
which  every  single  item  of  knowledge  or  experience,  and  con 
sequently  every  specific  judgment,  develops  its  full  intent 
and  implication  only  when  seen  in  relation  to  other  items  of 


152  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

knowledge  and  other  judgments,  is  the  most  adequate 
regulative  ideal  of  truth.  I  should  be  ready  to  show  (if  this 
were  the  place)  that  pragmatism  as  a  method  really  pre 
supposes,  when  its  implications  are  fully  thought  out,  the 
coherence  criterion  and  that  without  it  the  new  logical  realism 
can  be  nothing  more  than  the  subjective  and  introspective 
analysis  by  every  thinker  of  what  he  finds  in  his  own  so- 
called  intuitions. 

But  monistic  idealists  have  been  wont  to  go  farther  than 
this  (Hegel,  Bradley,  and  Bosanquet,  for  example),  and  to 
maintain  that  the  coherence  ideal  is  more  than  a  regulative 
ideal  in  truth-seeking.  They  have  been  wont  to  affirm  that 
it  expresses  the  ultimate  and  eternal  structure  of  reality,  and 
they  have  understood  this  to  mean  that  absolute  reality  is 
forever  one  completely  harmonious  and  timelessly  perfect 
whole. 

Their  metaphysical  use  of  the  principle  of  coherence  in 
volves  the  reduction  of  the  whole  temporal  order  of  expe 
rience  to  a  mere  appearance  of  a  timeless  whole,  with  the 
additional  result  that  they  are  equivocal  (Hegel),  or  cryptic 
and  unintelligible  (Bradley  and  Bosanquet),  both  as  to  how 
the  timelessly  perfect  reality  comes  to  appear  as  a  discrete 
succession  of  temporal  events,  and  as  to  what  may  be  the 
status  of  the  humanly  significant  features  of  the  temporal 
order  in  this  timeless  absolute. 

The  treatment  of  the  problems  of  causality  and  teleology 
by  monistic  idealists  affords  capital  illustrations  of  these  de 
fects.  The  difficulties  involved  in  thinking  out  causation, — 
the  puzzle  of  continuity,  that  is,  the  selection  of  a  point  when 
the  cause  ceases  and  the  effect  begins;  the  question  whether 
there  is  any  interval  of  time  between  them;  the  manner  in 
which  empty  time  can  make  a  difference  in  the  maturation 
of  a  causal  process;  the  fact  that  what  are  commonly  selected 
as  the  causes  of  a  phenomenon  are  more  or  less  arbitrarily 
picked  out  from  an  indefinite  multitude  of  conditions;  the 
problem  of  the  endless  regress  of  terms  and  relations  and 
the  so-called  plurality  of  causes, — all  these  are  regarded  as 
inescapable  difficulties,  to  be  solved  only  by  recognizing  that 


TIME  AND  MONISTIC  IDEALISM  153 

the  causal  relation  is  an  incomplete  or  phenomenal  expression 
of  the  principle  of  timeless  ground  or  logical  system.  Carry 
out  this  solution  to  its  logical  conclusion  and  the  causal  rela 
tion  is  then  simply  one  of  the  forms  of  illusory  (and  unac 
countable)  appearance,  in  a  temporal  plurality,  of  the  one 
eternal  system.  If  there  are  no  real  elements,  really  inter 
active  and  inter-patient,  then  the  whole  temporal  process  is 
inscrutably  appearance.  The  monistic  idealist,  when  asked 
what  use  causal  conceptions  have  in  practical  life  and  in 
science,  can  only  reply  that  they  are  useful  fictions  for  dealing 
with  phenomena.  In  the  system  of  timeless  reality  there 
can  be  no  causes  and  no  effects.  The  idealist  of  this  type 
never  faces  the  dilemma:  either  causal  changes  affect  'real' 
reality  and  reality  is  then  not  a  timeless  totality,  or  they  do 
not  affect  reality  and  then  experiential  actuality  is  an  illu 
sion.  No  wonder  that  the  biological  evolutionist  or  the 
experimental  physicist,  when  told  that  this  is  philosophy, 
passes  it  by  with  silent  contempt. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  monistic  idealist's  treatment  of 
causality  is  a  natural  consequence  of  his  manner  of  taking 
the  principles  of  identity  of  nature,  and  continuity  of  being, 
as  logical  leit-motifs  for  a  theory  of  science  and  reality. 
Bosanquet  has,  with  especial  insight  and  fertility  of  illus 
tration,  argued  for  the  principle  of  identity-in-difference  as 
the  fundamental  law  of  thought  and  reality.  But  I  think 
that  he  transcends  the  bounds  of  a  logic  of  science  or  a  logic 
of  experience  in  his  use  of  this  principle.  He  passes  insen 
sibly  from  similarity  of  type,  in  quality  or  relationship,  be 
tween  discrete  entities  to  ontological  identity.  All  that  a 
logic  of  science  need  postulate  of  its  objects  is  that,  though 
both  qualitatively  and  quantitatively  discrete,  they  are 
operative  in  relations  which  can  be  classified  into  types. 
All  the  community  of  condition  that  the  objects  which  enter 
into  a  specific  field  of  science  need  possess  is  mutual  relevancy 
of  behavior. 

Elemental  entities  may  be  related  so  that  they  are  capable 
of  being  made  a  whole  for  thought,  as  exhibiting  an  intel 
ligible  tissue  of  relationships,  while  yet  they  are  discrete 


154  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

members  in  a  moving  or  developing  system,  such  as  the  cells 
in  an  organism  or,  still  better,  the  individual  members  of  a 
society.  The  law  of  identity  properly  means  that  to  judge 
and  infer  we  must  postulate  that  there  are  individua  which 
may  be  regarded  for  purposes  of  logic  and  science  as  invariant 
objects  of  thought. 

I  am  willing  to  admit  that  all  actual  entities  or  individua^ 
and  all  relationships  which  they  sustain,  must  be,  now  or  at 
any  other  given  moment  of  time,  internal  to  the  totality  of 
the  real.  To  say  this  is  to  say  no  more  than  that,  in  knowing, 
we  are  dealing  with  our  data  as  parts  of  a  universal  order, 
whatever  that  may  be.  But  this  settles  nothing  as  to  the 
relative  degrees  of  independence  and  self-determination  to  be 
accorded  to  the  individual  members  of  the  total  reality.  It 
settles  nothing  whatever  as  to  the  specific  characters  and 
degrees  of  interrelationship  of  any  two  or  more  entities  or 
types  of  entity. 

I  admit  that,  to  comprehend  the  ground  of  the  being  and 
behavior  of  anything,  or  of  the  occurrence  of  any  event,  is  to 
gain  an  insight  into  the  system  of  connections  or  determinate 
orders  in  which  that  specific  datum  lives  and  moves  and  has 
its  being.  Every  sustained  effort  towards  the  reflective  or 
ganization  and  the  unification  of  empirical  data  involves 
the  faith  that  the  Universe  with  which  thought  traffics  is  in 
a  considerable  degree  an  orderly  or  systematic  whole,  the 
successive  phases  of  whose  history  are  in  part  at  least  intel 
ligibly  continuous. 

But  to  admit  all  this  settles  nothing  as  to  the  precise  de 
gree  and  manner  in  which  the  being  and  behavior  of  any 
elemental  entity  has  its  ground  respectively  within  and  with 
out  itself,  or  as  to  the  degree  in  which  the  successive  phases 
of  the  actual  behavior  and  qualities  of  anything  that  is  real 
could  be  now  determined,  if  one  had  a  complete  insight  into 
the  totality  of  relationships  in  which  all  real  entities  at 
present  stand  to  one  another. 

If  time  and  change  are  to  disappear  from  our  interpretation 
of  reality  just  in  the  measure  in  which  that  interpretation 
nears  completeness,  then  both  mechanical-causal  and  tel- 


TIME  AND  MONISTIC  IDEALISM  155 

eological  interpretations  of  the  experience-process  vanish  or 
become  meaningless  just  when  they  reach  their  fruitions.  In 
brief,  if  the  logical  ideal  of  knowledge  is  taken  to  involve  the 
absolute  monistic  conception  of  reality  as  the  timeless  whole 
or  system,  then  both  the  experience  from  which  the  thinker 
sets  out  and  the  logical  activity  of  his  thinking  are  illusory 
guides  which  lure  him  only  to  self-annihilation  and  the 
annihilation  of  his  world. 

Knowledge  means  the  comprehension  at  once  of  the  mu 
tual  relevancies  or  orderly  relationships  of  the  many  dis 
tinct  entities  which  constitute  reality,  and  of  the  uniqueness 
of  the  being  of  each  entity.  It  means  both  the  grasp  of 
the  successive  phases  of  actuality  as  orderly  series  or  con 
tinuous  sequences,  and  the  recognition  of  the  uniqueness  of 
each  phase  in  the  temporal  process  or  order. 

The  principle  of  continuity  is  illegitimately  used  as  a 
scientific  method,  if  it  be  taken  to  mean  that,  in  the  deter 
mination  of  causal  sequences  and  in  the  formulation  of  laws 
of  change,  the  discrete  moments  of  experience  must  be  made 
continually  smaller  and  smaller  until  they  disappear  in  a 
timeless  continuity  of  being.  The  principle  of  continuity 
legitimately  means  that  analysis  of  a  process  or  complex 
should  be  carried  as  far  as  possible.  But  there  are  elemental 
discontinuities  in  the  qualitative  processes  of  even  the  phys 
ical  world.  There  are  many  kinds  of  critical  points  in  phys 
ical  and  chemical  changes.  There  are  still  more  complex 
and  striking  discontinuities  in  vital  and  psychical  processes. 
All  that  continuity  means,  with  reference  to  the  analysis  and 
comprehension  of  change,  is  contained  in  the  notions  of  order 
or  serial  sequence  and  of  the  conservation  of  the  most  elemental 
features  of  the  process  throughout  the  transformation;  for 
example,  the  continuity  of  space,  time,  energy,  and  mass  in 
physics.  Continuity  means  in  physics  the  quantitative  con 
servation  of  energy,  but  with  significant  qualitative  dis 
continuities;  in  the  philosophy  of  spirit,  the  metaphysics  of 
ethics  and  religion,  it  means  conservation  of  values  with 
significant  creativity  of  values. 

The  treatment  of  teleology  in  the  logic  of  eternalistic  or 


156  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

monistic  idealism  is  even  more  equivocal  than  the  treatment 
of  causation.  Although  idealism  would  seem  to  imply,  if 
it  have  any  single  implication,  a  teleological  conception  of 
reality,  yet  since  teleology  involves  time  and  discrete  terms 
or  novelties,  the  eternalistic  or  monistic  idealist  is  forced  to 
regard  teleology  as  a  form  of  appearance  just  as  causation  in 
general  is,  though  indeed  a  higher  and  somewhat  truer  form 
of  appearance,  since  teleological  continuity  has  more  in 
dividuality  of  organized  system  than  causal  continuity. 
Even  Royce,  notwithstanding  his  speculative  ingenuity  in 
the  treatment  of  time  and  the  deeds  and  destinies  of  finite 
selves,  fails  to  show  how  these  temporal  deeds  and  lives  can 
be  constituent  elements  in  a  timeless  whole,  the  Eternal 
Self.  Bosanquet's  position  is  more  consequent.  For  him, 
the  absolute  timeless  whole  is  not  a  self  and  teleology  is  a 
sub-form  of  individuality.  Therefore,  personality  is,  of  neces 
sity,  an  appearance,  although,  since  one  appearance  differeth 
from  another  in  glory,  a  personality  is  more  real  than  a  mere 
biological  individual  and  this  in  turn  more  real  than  an  atom. 
But  personal  immortality  is  of  no  central  importance  in  eter- 
*  nalistic  idealism.  Progress  takes  place  in  the  absolute  whole 
or  individual,  but  this  does  not  progress  as  a  whole.  How 
progress  can  take  place  in  such  a  whole  we  are  not  told.  What 
sort  of  teleology  is  admissible  from  this  viewpoint?  The 
teleology  of  an  eternally  perfect  organization,  a  cosmos,  the 
timeless  self-maintenance  of  the  absolute  individuality. 
By  an  endless  series  of  compensating  adjustments,  interplays, 
and  redistributions  of  factors  in  its  finite  and  temporal  con 
stituents,  the  timeless  Absolute  maintains  its  equipoise. 
Let  us  be  specific.  In  that  minute,  ephemeral  part  of  the 
Absolute's  life  which  we  may  call  the  present  terrestrial  in 
ternational  maelstrom,  what  appears  to  its  constituent 
atoms  to  be  a  considerable  disturbance  is  now  going  on. 
Suppose  the  United  States  enters  the  fray,  and  suppose, 
further,  that  the  Central  Powers  are  forced  to  sue  for  peace 
in  1918.  A  redistribution  of  political  sovereignties  takes 
place.  A  League  of  Democratic  Nations  to  enforce  peace 
is  formed.  A  profound  and  far-reaching  social  reorganiza- 


TIME  AND  MONISTIC  IDEALISM  157 

tion  and  integration  is  slowly  and  toilsomely  achieved. 
Political,  economic,  and  social  life;  art,  literature,  science, 
education,  and  religion  are  greatly  modified.  Suppose  that 
in  the  total  outcome  the  twenty-first  century  should  differ 
from  the  nineteenth  much  more  than  the  sixteenth  from  the 
tenth  century  of  our  era.  What  has  happened  from  the 
standpoint  of  the  Absolute?  This  important  teleological 
alteration  in  civilization  (important  from  the  most  compre 
hensive  human  point  of  view)  cannot  alter  the  absolute 
individual,  or  disturb  its  passionless  serenity  one  whit.  Sup 
pose  we  call  the  change  i  progress.'  Then,  in  the  Absolute, 
there  must  have  been  going  on,  in  the  opposite  direction,  a 
retrogressive  equalizing  change,  by  which  the  serene  equi 
poise  of  the  Absolute  is  maintained.  In  the  Absolute  there 
is  neither  gain  nor  loss  in  existence  or  value,  only  the  Eternal 
Calm.  Human  beings  strive  with  might  and  main  for  the 
creation  of  new  values,  but  there  must  be  always  a  com 
pensating  process  of  annihilation  of  values,  in  order  that  the 
Absolute's  perfection  may  not  be  marred  or  its  repose 
ruffled. 

Thus,  on  the  whole,  progress  is  an  illusion.  And  what  mo 
tives  dictate  the  conclusion?  Not  the  motives  of  a  logic  of 
experience,  but  of  a  logic  by  which  the  meaning  of  experience 
is  condemned  ab  ante  under  the  rule  of  the  canons  of  absolute 
self-identity,  changeless  self-maintenance,  the  exclusive  per 
fection  and  value  of  the  timelessly  coherent  system,  a  logic 
which  springs  from  the  same  motives  as  quietism  in  morals 
and  contemplative,  world-fleeing  mysticism  in  religion. 

I  submit  that  the  idealist  cannot  keep  his  cake  and  eat  it 
in  this  temporal  world.  If  he  can  do  both  in  his  Absolute, 
he  is  more  than  human,  and  mere  humans  cannot  follow  him. 
He  cannot  be  a  devotee  of  the  timeless  Absolute  and  a  tel- 
eologist.  Purpose,  value,  progress,  selfhood,  individuality, 
are  categories  that  have  meaning  and  validity  only  in  applica 
tion  to  a  temporally  pluralistic  universe.  The  absolute,  all- 
inclusive,  timeless  individual  is  a  static  mechanism,  even 
though  it  be  christened  'spirit'  by  its  devotees.  The  bap 
tismal  ceremony  does  not  magically  spiritualize  it.  Intrinsic 


158  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

values  inhere  and  operate  only  in  conscious  selves  who  act 
to  achieve  and  create  and  conserve  experienced  values. 
This  activity  is  the  only  kind  of  purposiveness  one  can 
clearly  conceive.  Unconscious  teleology  is  such  only  in  the 
light  of,  and  in  subservience  to,  conscious  teleology.  Tel 
eology  means  process  and  hence  involves  time.  A  timeless 
whole  is  non-teleological,  hence  mechanical. 

The  fundamental  issues  in  a  philosophy  which  faces  the 
problem  of  time  and  evolution,  and  is  not  content  to  pass  it 
over  with  cryptic  sayings  as  to  its  being  an  *  appearance,' 
'transmuted,'  'absorbed,'  or  'transcended'  in  the  Eternal 
Absolute,  are  the  relative  positions  to  be  occupied  by  the 
categories  of  continuity  and  discreteness  in  the  interpretation 
of  experience.  Continuity  and  discreteness  are  the  basic 
categories  of  science  and  metaphysics  and  hence  of  logic. 
Every  other  category, — causation,  change,  substance,  tel 
eology,  individuality, — is  a  sub-form  blended  of  continuity 
and  discreteness,  of  the  universal  or  relation,  which,  taken 
by  itself,  seems  a  timeless  type,  and  the  individual,  the 
'this,'  which  is  the  discretely  experienced  fact  or  appreciat 
ing,  interested,  attitude-taking  self  that  lives  and  traffics 
in  time.  Bradley  and  Bosanquet  have  indeed  seen  the 
problem  in  its  irreducible  elements,  but  their  Absolute  solves 
the  problem  by  abolishing  its  more  basic  and  substantive 
factor,  the  immediate,  discrete,  temporal  reality.  Their 
absolute,  timeless  individuality  abolishes  individuality. 

I  have  not  space  here  for  more  than  dogmatic  assertion 
and  hints.  I  must,  therefore,  be  content  to  say  that,  in  logic 
and  metaphysics,  if  our  interpretations  are  to  be  adequate 
to  the  nature  of  experience  and  the  ineluctable  quality  of  life, 
which  we  seek  to  understand  and  to  sublimate  into  thought- 
forms,  we  must  recognise  that  discreteness,  in  the  form  of 
qualitative  novelty  as  well  as  of  quantitative  multiplicity 
in  its  elements  and  in  the  serial  orders  of  its  evolutionary 
processes,  is  to  be  taken  as  an  inexpugnable  feature  of  reality. 

The  same  logical  error  is  found  in  the  absolute  monistic 
idealists  as  in  Spinoza.  The  principle  of  ground,  located  in 
a  timeless  sytem,  is  made  both  the  canonical  criterion  of 


TIME  AND  MONISTIC  IDEALISM  159 

knowledge  and  the  constitutive  principle  of  being.  But,  for 
a  logic  of  experience,  the  principle  of  ground  is  neither  log 
ically  nor  psychologically  primitive.  It  is  derived,  by  a 
process  of  abstractive  construction,  from  the  principle  of 
causation,  which  I  take  to  be  identical  with  the  principle  of 
sufficient  reason.  There  must  be  sufficient  grounds  for  every 
occurrence:  this  is  a  postulate  of  science.  *  Cause'  is  the 
sufficient  temporal  ground  of  an  event.  The  relation  of 
cause  and  effect  is  logically  primitive.  It  is  not  legitimate 
to  seek  the  sufficient  ground  of  temporal  occurrence  in  a  non- 
temporal  systematic  ground.  Such  procedure  is  a  passage 
into  an  entirely  different  genus.  And  it  is  absurd  to  seek 
a  sufficient  ground  for  the  original  structure  of  reality.  That 
structure  is  its  own  eternal  ground. 

It  follows  that  the  postulate  of  continuity  or  uniformity 
is  illegitimately  used,  if  it  be  taken  to  imply  that  all  qual 
itative  discreteness  and  temporal  discontinuity  must  be 
metamorphosed  into  absolute  homogeneity  and  timeless 
continuity.  The  monistic  idealist  seems  here  the  slave  of  the 
logical  vice  of  which  Herbert  Spencer's  legerdemain  in  pro 
ducing  heterogeneity  from  homogeneity  is  so  signal  an 
example.  ^Continuity  means  nothing  more  than  that  there 
are  types  of  relationships  or  relevancies  of  one  element  of 
reality  to  others  (the  types  to  be  empirically  determined), 
and  that,  in  so  far  as  qualitatively  similar  elements  are  found 
in  temporally  discrete  situations,  qualitatively  similar  se 
quences  may  be  expected.  The  postulate  of  uniformity  is 
that  the  same  causes  will  probably  have  the  same  effects. 
Nothing  is  implied  as  to  how  far  the  same  causes  are  ever 
actually  repeated.)  Reality  as  experienced  (including  the 
results  of  the  most  rigorous  analysis  in  'experience')  is  an 
indefinitely  vast  and  loosely  related  system  of  qualitative 
complexes,  ever  producing  new  qualitative  complexes.  Ac 
tual  reality  shows  indefinite  gradings  of  relevancies  and 
irrelevancies  among  its  individua.  (We  isolate  now  this  now 
that  type  of  relevancy,  but  perhaps  no  two  moments  in  the 
temporal  process  are  ever  exactly  the  same.) 

I  would  then  substitute  for  the  principle  of  identity-in- 


160  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

difference,  as  the  primary  postulate  of  scientific  thinking, 
the  principle  of  relevancy  or  the  principle  of  similarity  of  rela 
tionships.  All  science  and  all  intelligent  practice  proceed 
upon  the  assumption  that  there  are  discoverable  types  of 
relationship  between  the  qualities  of  the  real  and  between 
those  complexes  of  qualities  which  constitute  individual 
elements  of  the  real.  To  say  that  one  type  of  sequence  or 
co-existence  is  relevant  to  another  case,  present  or  prospec 
tive,  is  to  say  that  there  is  here  a  similarity  of  relationship 
in  the  behavior  of  different  groups  of  things,  sequent  or  co 
existent  as  the  case  may  be. 

Instead  of  turning  the  postulate  of  continuity  into  the  de 
mand  for  a  timeless  identity  of  being,  a  changeless  self- 
maintenance  of  being,  I  hold  that  continuity,  as  a  logical 
postulate,  means  nothing  more  than  the  demand  that  analy 
sis  of  the  co-existential  or  sequential  data  shall  be  carried  to 
as  fine  a  point  as  may  be,  without  substituting  for  experienced 
fact  conceptual  fictions  that  are  non-experiential  in  the  sense 
that  they  never  have  been  and  never  could  be  experienced 
under  conceivable  conditions.  Such  a  conceptual  fiction  is 
the  principle  of  'timeless  ground.'  {^Instead  of  taking  the 
principle  of  coherence  or  consistency  to  mean  that  every 
thing  and  event  must  somehow  now  and  always  be  trans 
muted  into  the  timeless  perfection  of  the  absolute  system,  I 
would  take  the  principle  of  coherence  as  a  regulative  ideal  or 
demand  of  both  thought  and  feeling- volition :  the  demand  of 
thought  to  satisfy  itself  by  attaining  the  fullest  consistency  or 
coherent  relevancy  in  the  interrelationships  of  the  elements  of 
the  temporal  process;  the  demand  of  feeling  volition  for  the 
fullest  harmony  of  organic  unity  of  personal  experience.  J 

Thus,  the  sound  standpoint  in  both  logic  and  metaphysics 
for  me  is  not  an  organic  eternalism  but  organizational  Tem- 
poralism.  In  other  words,  experience  is  in  process  of  or 
ganization, — personal,  social,  and  cosmical, — and  the  func 
tion  by  which  it  fulfils  itself  and  ministers  to  life  is  the 
furtherance  of  the  organization  of  reality  and,  through  this 
organization,  the  harvesting  of  richer  values  in  experience. 

A  ideologically  ordered  universe  must  be  pluralistic  in 


TIME  AND  MONISTIC  IDEALISM  161 

the  status  and  relationships  of  its  elements.  The  kinds  and 
degrees  of  unity  and  continuity  in  such  a  universe  can  be 
determined  empirically  only  in  the  light  of  a  recognition  of 
original  and  persisting  discretenesses,  the  plurality  of  many 
individua  or  unitary,  qualitative  complexes  in  multiple  re 
lationship.  The  original  continuity  of  the  universe  can  con 
sist  only  in  the  original  interdependencies,  or  orders  of  rela 
tionship,  among  the  plural  entities  which  constitute  it.  The 
permanent  continuity  (if  there  be  such)  can  consist  only  in 
the  active  perduration  and  increase  (perhaps)  of  the  societal 
or  solidaire  interdependence  of  its  elements,  as  these  are 
modified  and  modify  others,  are  engendered  and  engender 
other  elements,  in  the  ordering  process  of  the  whole.  Thus 
the  only  admissible  eternity  is  that  of  the  perduration  of  an 
active  ground  of  order,  direction,  and  harmony,  enduring 
and  growing  in  its  scope  as  energizing  being,  through  the  in 
crease  and  fruition  of  the  elemental  constituents  of  its  world 
in  their  internal  harmonies  and  societal  interdependences. 
The  only  metaphysical  conception  that  will  square  with 
the  logic  of  actual  experience  is  thus  temporalistic  plural 
ism.  By  this  I  mean  a  metaphysics  which  holds  that  there 
can  be  no  reality  which  does  not  traffic  in  time,  no  timeless 
being  or  beings;  which  holds  it  absurd  to  suppose  time  and 
process  to  have  had  beginnings,  since  beginnings  imply  tem 
poral  antecedents,  and  therefore  equally  absurd  to  suppose 
a  surcease  of  temporal  process;  which  holds  that  the  actual 
changefulness,  the  epigenetic  movement  of  reality  towards 
fuller,  richer,  more  harmonious  individuality,  as  one  passes, 
in  one's  survey,  from  qualitative  discontinuities  in  the  phys 
ical  order  to  more  striking  discontinuities  in  the  vital, 
psychical,  and  historical-cultural  orders,  is  inconceivable,  un 
thinkable,  and  inexplicable,  unless  we  suppose  that  a  plural 
ity  of  discrete  elements  (many  individua),  entering  into  a 
multitude  of  transactions  with  each  other,  give  rise  to  further 
temporally  discrete,  and  therefore  novel,  entities  in  the  cease 
less  dynamic  process  of  actuality.1 

1  The  above  essay  is  a  very  summary  abstract  of  the  underlying  logic 
of  my  forthcoming  work,  Personality  and  the  World. 


THE  DATUM 
WALTER  BOWERS  PILLSBURY 

EVERY  philosophy,  and  for  that  matter  every  science, 
presupposes  a  datum,  something  upon  which  it  may  build. 
This  it  is  that  gives  justification  for  the  later  developments 
and  upon  it  later  statements  are  made  to  rest.  Unfortu 
nately  in  science  and  philosophy,  and  even  in  common  sense, 
no  agreement  exists  as  to  what  the  datum  is  or  even  as  to 
what  its  function  should  be.  One  man's  datum  is  another 
man's  conclusion,  and  vice  versa.  Systems  can  obviously  be 
divided  into  two  great  groups  on  the  basis  of  the  kind  of 
datum  they  assume  or  seek.  For  one,  the  datum  is  a  gen 
eral  principle  or  a  system  of  principles,  or  abstractions  of 
other  sorts;  for  the  other,  the  datum  is  a  more  or  less  con 
crete  experience.  On  the  one  hand,  we  have  Plato,  Spinoza, 
Kant,  and  Hegel,  together  with  the  mathematicians  and  all 
rationalists;  on  the  other,  stand  Hume  and  the  positivists, 
in  less  degree,  Locke,  Condillac,  Avenarius,  and  the  empir 
ical  scientists.  For  the  first  school,  observation  must  give 
way  to  universal  laws  and  pre-established  principles;  for  the 
second,  these  principles  derive  their  validity,  so  far  as  they 
have  validity,  from  their  agreement  with  experience.  The 
two  schools  are  as  far  apart  as  it  is  possible  to  be  in  state 
ment  and  in  temperament. 

Closer  examination  shows  that  the  differences  are  more  in 
the  general  statements  and  the  ideals  of  what  should  be  the 
nature  of  truth  or  of  proof  than  in  the  actually  accepted  first 
principles.  Neither  accepts  the  actually  experienced  as  the 
given,  and  both  implicitly  or  explicitly  look  to  the  given  for 
the  justification  of  their  principles.  This  first  statement  is 
self-evident  and  self-asserted  for  the  conceptualists.  They 
deny  that  they  need,  or  even  that  there  is,  immediate  expe 
rience.  The  warrant  they  usually  find  in  something  superior 


THE  DATUM  163 

or  anterior  to  experience.  As  we  shall  see,  however,  they 
all  finally  come  back  to  the  primary  experience  they  deny 
to  exist  as  final  warrant  for  their  statements.  The  soi  disant 
empiricists,  however,  are  not  so  close  to  immediate  expe 
rience  as  they  would  have  us  believe.  What  they  assume  is 
really  not  experienced,  but  is  a  concept  assumed  to  explain 
experience.  The  sensations  of  Locke  and  Condillac,  even 
the  impressions  and  ideas  of  Hume,  are  never  found  in  real 
consciousness.  They  are  unlike  any  actual  objects  or  men 
tal  states.  They  are  regarded  as  elements  from  which  real 
things  or  ideas  may  be  compounded,  but  the  strongest  up 
holder  of  the  sensational  doctrine  would  not  claim  that  any 
one  actually  experiences  them.  Like  the  general  principles 
of  the  rationalists,  they  are  constructions,  and  their  only 
excuse  for  being  is  that  they  may  serve  to  explain  how  expe 
rience  is  possible  or  might  be  possible.  These  views  are 
empirical  only  in  so  far  as  they  assert  that  all  must  have 
come  in  some  way  through  experience,  but  when  they  at 
tempt  any  positive  explanation,  they  at  once  deviate  widely 
from  experience.  Even  Hume  in  his  positive  constructions 
lays  himself  open  to  the  same  charge,  although  on  the  neg 
ative  side  he  disposes  of  all  that  any  one  could  wish  to 
eliminate. 

In  the  more  recent  systems,  the  theory  of  Avenarius  and 
the  similar  doctrine  of  Wundt  in  some  of  his  later  writings 
most  nearly  approach  a  truly  empirical  datum.  The  assump 
tion  is  that  all  goes  back  to  a  pure  experience  in  which  at 
first  there  is  neither  mental  nor  physical,  but  from  which  all 
that  is  physical  or  mental  may  develop  as  a  result  of  more 
or  less  conscious  thought  and  comparison.  The  original 
experience  has  neither  things  nor  mental  states  and  even 
nothing  of  reference  to  things  or  mental  states,  but  out  of  it 
we  build  our  things  or  substantive  elements  and  also  our 
general  laws.  Even  in  this  theory  we  do  not  get  back  to  real 
experience.  Their  immediate  experience  is  unintelligible 
because  it  has  not  been  interpreted;  the  world  as  we  know 
it  is  a  development  of  a  more  or  less  arbitrary  sort  from  that. 
Here  again  we  deal  not  with  the  immediately  known  but 


164  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

with  an  inference  from  that  known,  which  has  been  made  to 
explain  it.  The  world  of  pure  experience  is  a  pure  assump 
tion,  on  the  same  level  as  Plato's  ideas  or  Kant's  categories  or 
Locke's  sensations.  It  is  an  imaginary  picture  of  how  knowl 
edge  might  have  developed.  It  is  assumed,  not  really  given. 
While  none  of  these  theories  discovers  the  real  datum, 
they  all  imply  it.  All  that  is  necessary  to  find  it  is  to  put 
their  implications  in  the  place  of  their  direct  assertions. 
What  all  imply  is  that  we  are  immediately  aware  of  some 
thing, — that  we  know,  without  emphasis  upon  either  the  'we' 
or  the  knowing  or  the  thing  known.  After  accepting  this 
they  each  and  all  try  to  reduce  it  to  something  else,  to  sensa 
tions  or  mental  states,  to  atoms  or  to  ions,  to  concepts  or 
categories,  and  when  once  they  have  started  upon  the  process 
of  reduction,  they  forget  the  starting  point  and  mistake 
their  assumptions  and  conclusions  for  the  really  given  or  the 
immediately  known.  As  opposed  to  the  pure  experience  of 
Avenarius,  it  is  that  experience  as  it  has  been  developed  by 
each  individual  for  his  practical  needs  and  before  he  has 
transformed  it  by  trying  to  discover  what  it  is  as  knowledge 
and  how  it  originates.  It  is  just  the  table  as  I  write  upon  it 
and  the  pen  with  which  I  write  and  the  ideas  that  come  or 
will  not  come  or  at  least  the  feeling  of  discouragement  that 
I  fail  to  express  them  as  I  wish  that  I  could.  These  are  the 
realities;  these  are  immediate;  these  are  the  data  with  which 
every  science,  every  philosophy,  and  for  that  matter  every 
practical  man  in  his  practical  moods  must  start,  whether  he 
explain  them  or  merely  use  them.  In  other  words,  it  is  the 
real  experience  as  it  exists  at  any  given  moment;  it  is  expe 
rience  produced  by  all  of  the  forces  of  life,  after  everything 
has  acted  upon  it  that  really  does  act  upon  it,  rather  than 
any  abstraction,  whether  the  simple  elements  out  of  which 
experience  may  be  assumed  to  be  compounded  or  an  un 
developed  matrix  assumed  to  be  present  before  the  various 
forces  have  worked  upon  it  in  any  way.  It  is  the  completed 
knowledge,  or  at  least  the  actual  knowledge,  rather  than  the 
embryo  knowledge.  It  is  the  whole  and  the  immediate 
rather  than  the  analyzed  or  the  abstract. 


THE  DATUM  165 

To  make  the  assumption  that  the  given  is  the  experience 
as  we  actually  have  it,  rather  than  some  abstraction  which 
will  explain  that  experience,  amounts  almost  to  an  inversion 
of  the  ordinary  statement.  It  consist  practically  in  standing 
the  usual  philosophical  or  scientific  system  upon  its  head.  To 
be  sure,  such  systems  tacitly  assume  this  datum  as  they  begin 
their  discussions  but  assume  it  only  to  forget  it.  They  be 
come  involved  in  sensations  or  concepts  or  universals  or  a 
priori  forms  or  categories,  on  the  one  side,  and  in  atoms, 
ions,  ether,  and  what  not,  on  the  other,  and  in  these  they 
forget  the  reality  with  which  they  started.  They  even 
attempt  to  pass  off  these  assumptions  as  reality  when  they 
become  fully  sophisticated,  although  they  are  struck  now 
and  again  with  the  differences  between  what  they  have  in 
immediate  experience  and  the  results  of  their  various  con 
structions.  They  check  up  by  comparison  with  the  real 
from  time  to  time.  Like  Antaeus,  they  receive  new  strength 
when  they  touch  the  earth,  but  the  contacts  are  so  far  apart 
that  they  are  prone  to  disregard  the  source  of  their  virility. 

Granting  that  the  datum  is  the  immediate  knowledge  or  is 
to  be  found  in  things  as  they  are,  obviously  we  must  attempt 
to  come  to  closer  quarters  with  it  by  way  of  description  or 
definition.  This  is  difficult  because  of  its  very  simplicity  or 
immediateness.  One  cannot  describe  the  datum  without 
comparing  it  with  something  else,  and  the  description  is 
likely  to  be  taken  seriously  as  meaning  that  it  is  something 
else.  One  may  attempt,  as  in  the  game  of  twenty  questions, 
to  run  it  to  earth  by  answering  yes  or  no  to  a  number  of  the 
more  frequent  disjunctions.  First,  is  it  mental  or  material? 
One  must  deny  that  this  question  may  be  asked.  The  datum 
is  indifferent  to  the  distinction.  Mind  and  matter  are  both 
ways  of  interpreting  the  actually  given,  but  the  datum  itself 
may  be  regarded  as  either  or  both  without  changing  its 
fundamental  character.  One  thing  must  be  asserted  pos 
itively,  and  that  is  that  the  given  as  such  does  not  divide 
into  two  parts,  a  mental  and  a  physical.  It  may  have  mental 
aspects  and  physical  aspects,  but  one  part  cannot  be  said 
to  be  mental,  the  other  physical,  as  is  so  frequently  asserted. 


166  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

In  any  case  the  datum  is  primary  and  real;  the  interpretation 
is  secondary.  One  may  therefore  leave  the  discussion  of  the 
interpretations  for  the  present. 

A  second  fundamental  question  is  whether  the  datum  has 
meaning  or  acquires  it.  To  this  the  answer  is  unquestion 
able:  the  datum  is  meaning.  Nothing  can  be  appreciated 
without  meaning.  One  must  assert  with  Woodbridge  that 
awareness  and  meaning  are  identical.  The  datum  is  just 
what  it  means.1  What  it  may  be  as  thing  or  idea  may  be 
open  to  dispute;  it  may  even  be  disputed  whether  it  be  thing 
or  idea,  but  there  never  can  be  any  dispute  over  whether  or 
not  it  has  meaning.  One  must  object  to  the  assertion  of 
Bradley  that  one  may  be  aware  of  mental  states  first  and 
ascribe  meaning  to  them  later.  Awareness  and  meaning  go 
hand  in  hand  and  one  cannot  be  discriminated  from  the  other. 
Something  does  not  come  into  awareness  as  a  meaningless 
somewhat  and  then  gradually  assume  meaning;  on  the  con 
trary,  it  does  not  exist  before  it  acquires  meaning  and  when 
it  exists  it  is  just  that  meaning.  Much  the  same  statement 
may  be  made  with  reference  to  Dewey's  assertion  that  the 
judgment  confers  a  meaning  upon  a  meaningless  somewhat 
and  thus  makes  possible  the  distinction  between  the  mean 
ingful  and  the  antecedent  meaningless.  Everything  in 
experience  must  have  already  been  judged  before  it  can  be 
an  experience.  We  have  in  awareness  only  the  results  of 
judgments.  Nothing  exists  before  judgment  of  some  sort 
has  been  passed  upon  it.  In  short,  then,  all  philosophy  and 
all  science  must  begin  with  a  material  that  has  already  been 
interpreted  and  understood,  not  with  any  form  of  raw  mate 
rial.  It  has  for  the  most  part  been  interpreted  and  under 
stood  only  in  the  light  of  practical  needs;  the  question  as  to 
what  it  may  be  in  itself  has  not  yet  been  asked  about  it, 
but  it  must  be  assumed  to  be  the  result  of  much  elaboration 
rather  than  a  mere  first  raw  material. 

To  assert  that  the  given  is  just  the  real  experience  does  not 
take  us  very  far  on  the  way  to  an  answer  to  any  of  the  ques- 

1  Cf.  the  writer's  "Meaning  and  Image,"  Psychological  Review,  Vol.  XV, 
1908,  p.  150. 


THE  DATUM  167 

tions  that  any  one  is  really  interested  in.  One  cannot  have 
real  explanation  or  any  science  or  philosophy  if  one  stops 
with  that  statement.  One  may  be  quite  willing  to  admit 
that  trees  and  men  are  seen,  that  men  reach  certain  con 
clusions  as  they  reason,  that  they  feel  certain  emotions  when 
defeated,  but  no  one  who  thinks  at  all  deeply  can  stop  there, 
and  most  are  inclined  to  feel  that  any  one  of  these  admitted 
facts  is  subordinate  to  and  less  real  than  its  explanation. 
One  must  not  merely  insist  that  all  goes  back  to  the  given 
but  must  also  leave  room  for  an  explanation  of  the  given. 
The  most  frequent  interpretation  of  the  datum  is  found  in  the 
assertion  that  experience  is  of  things,  is  of  external  reality, 
with  the  implication  that  this  external  reality  is  to  be  taken 
for  granted.  In  the  different  sciences  the  original  experience 
is  referred  to  laws,  particular  or  general,  and  to  elements  of 
one  type  or  another.  In  the  crudest  forms  of  these  external 
explanations,  reality  is  said  to  be  composed  of  atoms  or  of 
four  elements,  combined  in  different  ways.  These  are  ob 
viously  only  explanations  or  interpretations;  there  is  nothing 
in  them  of  direct  observation.  Yet  the  men  who  proposed 
them  took  them  with  the  utmost  seriousness  and  believed 
that  the  atoms  were  real,  while  the  actual  experience  was  only 
appearance. 

This  tendency  to  believe  in  the  interpretations  as  the 
realities,  and  in  the  datum, — sounds,  colors,  sticks,  and 
stones, — as  deceptive,  is  universal.  Explanations  are  and 
must  be  made  by  every  one  in  all  connections,  whether  he  be 
scientist  or  philosopher  or  the  man  in  the  street.  There  is 
also  a  tendency  with  every  one  to  regard  the  interpretation  as 
real,  as  even  more  real  than  the  datum.  But  when  asked 
what  the  real  interpretation  is,  difference  of  opinion  is  bound 
to  arise,  since  in  almost  every  case  there  is  not  one  inter 
pretation  but  many,  and  the  advocate  of  each  holds  his  alone 
to  be  adequate.  One  can  both  illustrate  what  must  be  meant 
by  the  given  and  show  the  necessity  for  interpretation,  if 
one  considers  the  position  of  a  red  light  in  space.  The  imme 
diate  datum  is  that  the  red  light  is  directly  ahead  ten  feet 
distant  from  the  eye.  That  all  would  agree  upon.  It  is  the 


168  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

datum  for  each  observer  in  the  same  position.  But  the 
physiologist  will  at  once  say  that  the  red  color  cannot  be  in 
space  because  there  is  nothing  there  to  appreciate  it.  It  can 
be  no  more  than  a  stimulus  of  some  sort  upon  the  retina  of 
the  eye.  The  physicist  must  then  explain  that  it  is  only  the 
source  that  is  ten  feet  away,  but  that  from  the  source  the 
light  is  carried  in  some  way.  The  psychologist  connects 
this  fact,  that  lights  always  seem  to  be  where  they  (or  the 
stimuli)  are  not,  with  a  statement  of  the  conditions  of  seeing 
distance.  This  solves  the  problem  from  his  standpoint. 
One  may  add  the  interpretation  of  the  physiologist  regarding 
transmission  to  the  cortex  and  any  of  the  psychological  laws 
involved.  Each  of  these  is  an  interpretation  from  a  different 
point  of  view  and  each  may  well  claim  to  be  real.  Obviously, 
however,  not  all  can  be  real,  and  in  strict  impartiality  it  is 
difficult  to  see  that  one  has  a  better  claim  to  reality  than  any 
of  the  others.  The  one  thing  that  cannot  be  doubted  is  that 
the  red  light  is  out  there  ten  feet  from  the  eye.  All  explana 
tions  start  from  that  and  none  can  be  true  that  does  not  in 
some  way  harmonize  with  that  statement,  whatever  form 
it  may  be  given  in  the  course  of  the  explanations. 

This  does  not  mean  that  the  realist's  interpretation  of  the 
given  is  any  more  true  than  any  of  the  others.  The  datum  is 
not  necessarily  given  as  a  thing.  The  assertion  that  it  is 
external  is  no  more  immediately  certain  than  the  assertion 
that  it  is  mental.  To  assert  that  it  is  externally  real  at  once 
raises  the  question  whether  it  is  real  as  a  red  color,  real  as  a 
vibration  rate,  and  if  a  vibration  rate  whether  in  ether  or 
as  a  form  of  electrical  energy,  or  real  as  a  chemical  substance 
or  as  a  continuing  chemical  reaction.  It  must  be  at  least 
three  of  these  at  once  and  no  one  can  be  said  to  be  more 
real  than  any  other.  Probably  neither  the  physicist  nor  the 
chemist  would  be  willing  to  admit  the  real  existence  of  the 
red  color,  although  that  alone  is  really  experienced,  and  no 
two  interpreters  would  quite  agree  as  to  where  the  end  of  the 
analysis  that  constitutes  the  real  is  to  be  found.  This  asser 
tion  of  external  reality  does  not  simplify  our  problem,  does 
not  furnish  an  unambiguous  interpretation  upon  which  all 


THE  DATUM  169 

can  agree,  and  obviously  therefore  cannot  be  assumed  as  an 
axiom.  With  that  assertion  we  pass  away  from  our  datum 
to  an  explanation. 

Exactly  the  same  remarks  may  be  made  of  the  idealist's 
attempt  to  reduce  all  experience  to  sensation  or  conscious 
ness  or  idea.  This  again  is  an  explanation  for  which  much 
evidence  can  be  brought,  but  to  reduce  a  red  light  ten  feet 
from  the  eye  to  a  red  sensation  plus  double  images  of  back 
ground,  plus  strain  sensations,  plus  memories  of  other  spaces, 
etc.,  in  the  familiar  psychological  way,  does  not  leave  the 
original  experience  in  existence.  The  datum  must  be  the 
more  real  and  unless  these  explanations  can  be  shown  to 
make  possible  the  original  they  fail  even  as  explanations. 
Of  the  two  forms  of  explanation  the  realistic  more  nearly 
conforms  to  the  natural  inclinations  of  the  ordinary  man. 
Still  neither  is  real  in  the  same  sense  as  the  datum,  if  univer 
sal  acceptance  be  taken  as  the  test  of  reality. 

But  to  assume  that  the  datum,  the  immediate  awareness, 
is  the  real  does  not  mean  that  explanation  is  to  be  denied  all 
value.  It  is  not  necessary  that  an  explanation  be  accepted 
by  all,  or  even  that  the  different  explanations  should  be  con 
sistent,  to  give  each  value.  The  utility  of  the  explanation 
needs  no  advocate.  The  explanation  that  is  no  more  than 
a  reference  of  one  event  to  other  similar  ones  makes  state 
ment  more  easy,  and  at  the  same  time  gives  a  basis  for  the 
anticipation  of  other  events.  In  practice  it  is  easier  to  foresee 
the  future,  if  one  has  a  theory  and  the  outcome  justifies  the 
theory.  Much  of  the  test  as  well  as  the  justification  of 
theory  or  any  ot<her  form  of  explanation  is  pragmatic:  partly 
the  test  of  practical  application,  partly  the  test  of  working 
in  harmony  with  other  experiences.  It  is  this  effectiveness 
of  explanations  in  furthering  practical  ends,  in  furnishing 
the  means  of  advancement,  in  the  designing  of  instruments, 
the  building  of  useful  articles  and  machines  that  tends  to 
make  the  explanation  seem  more  real  even  than  the  datum. 
All  of  the  illusions  and  inconsistencies  of  immediate  expe 
rience  can  be  made  to  disappear  in  the  conceptual  construc 
tion,  so  that  each  in  its  place  will  provide  a  safer  ground  for 


170  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

thought  and  for  action  than  the  datum  itself.  For  all  of 
these  reasons,  as  well  as  because  it  satisfies  the  instinct  of 
curiosity,  we  cannot  avoid  theorizing  and  explaining. 

Even  in  the  most  fundamental  theories,  where  incon 
sistency  is  most  prevalent,  there  need  be  no  difficulty  in 
making  use  of  explanations.  One  must  in  these  cases,  how 
ever,  accept  the  explanation  as  a  means  to  an  end,  must 
consider  its  utility,  and  not  expect  absolute  consistency. 
If  the  justification  of  an  explanation  is  its  usefulness,  there 
is  no  reason  why  one  should  not  use  one  as  far  as  it  will  go, 
then  choose  another.  Our  red  light  may  be  a  vibration 
rate,  the  decomposition  of  lithium  salts,  the  stimulation 
of  a  peculiar  nerve  tissue,  and  even  an  elementary  sen 
sation,  all  at  the  same  time.  The  objection  felt  by  the 
traditional  philosopher  seems  to  depend  upon  the  belief  that 
his  explanation  must  be  something  final  and  absolute,  that 
it,  not  the  datum,  is  real.  If  that  be  real,  it  is  assumed  that 
it  is  the  real  and  that  to  assert  two  reals  at  the  same  time 
and  in  the  same  place  involves  inconsistency.  To  permit 
different  explanations  reduces  the  universe  to  chaos.  Take 
the  explanation  less  seriously,  assume  that  facts  are  facts  no 
matter  what  they  are  called,  and  the  difficulty  vanishes.  The 
red  light  is  the  real.  You  do  not  change  it  by  calling  it  a 
sensation  or  an  electric  wave  or  a  retinal  excitation;  you 
change  the  class  into  which  you  put  it, — you  change  its 
name, — but  all  that  does  not  affect  the  reality.  Thinking 
about  it  or  talking  about  it  does  it  neither  good  nor  harm, 
whatever  good  or  harm  it  may  do  the  philosopher  himself  or 
however  it  may  advance  or  retard  the  science. 

There  is  no  reason  why  one  should  not  be  both  a  realist 
and  an  idealist,  or  admit  the  truth  of  one's  realistic  and 
one's  idealistic  attitudes.  One  must  admit  that  there  are 
subjective  phases  of  experience  and  objective  phases  of  ex 
perience.  While  it  is  good  discipline  and  good  exercise  in 
argument  to  reduce  all  external  reality  to  idea,  or  all  ideas, 
through  complicated  mechanical  hypotheses,  to  interactions 
between  different  forms  of  matter,  it  does  not  change  the 
character  of  the  datum,  and  does  not  show  that  the  other 


THE  DATUM  171 

interpretation  is  not  still  possible.  In  connection  with  the 
body-mind  relation,  for  example,  one  can  find  good  proof 
that  an  experience  is  conscious,  that  it  is  made  possible  by  a 
brain  state,  and  that  it  is  ultimately  a  thing  in  the  physical 
universe,  but  it  is  not  possible  at  present  to  show  that  either 
one  or  the  other  is  not  true  nor  is  it  possible  to  reduce  all 
three  separate  explanations  to  a  single  consistent  one.  From 
our  present  point  of  view  it  is  convenient  to  let  them  all 
stand  side  by  side.  The  primary  fact  or  datum  is  the  same 
whichever  be  true.  One  may  add  the  pious  hope  that  some 
day  it  will  be  possible  to  combine  them  all  and  that  this 
ultimate  explanation,  whether  formula  or  phrase,  will  be  the 
real  truth.  But  that  does  not  prevent  one  from  accepting 
as  true  the  separate  partial  explanations  even  if  they  be 
inconsistent. 

Nor  need  we  be  prevented  from  carrying  on  the  search  for 
new  explanations  and  new  facts  by  this  acceptance  of  the 
indifference  to  the  facts  of  the  explanations  that  are  given 
of  them.  Practical  demands  for  short-hand  expression  of 
facts,  the  value  of  the  formulations  in  foreshadowing  other 
events,  and  above  all  the  instinct  of  curiosity,  which  demands 
that  every  event  be  related  to  some  other,  are  sufficient  to 
keep  the  process  of  interpretation  and  the  consequent  devel 
opment  of  science  and  philosophy  continuously  progressing. 
Even  if  my  assertion  that  explanation  is  always  less  real 
than  the  thing  explained  be  accepted,  it  would  have  no  in 
fluence  upon  the  movement,  for  to  be  consistent  I  should 
have  to  admit  my  interpretation  of  the  nature  of  thought  and 
of  investigation  to  be  less  real  than  the  science  itself.  It  is 
not  only  important  that  the  elements  of  the  datum  be  clas 
sified  properly,  that  observations  be  correlated,  but  this 
activity  could  not  be  stopped  if  one  tried.  While  explana 
tions  need  not  be  regarded  as  ever  giving  the  ultimately  real, 
perhaps  never  the  ultimate  truth,  they  have  an  important 
function  in  the  theoretical  and  practical  life,  a  function  that 
is  sufficiently  appreciated  in  common  usage  and  discussion 
and  need  not  be  insisted  upon  here. 

It  must  also  be  emphasized  in  justification  of  the  felt 


172  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

reality  of  explanations  that  it  is  very  difficult,  even  in  the 
simplest  cases,  to  distinguish  between  the  immediate  datum 
and  its  explanation.  The  accepted  explanations  of  percep 
tion  indicate  that  merely  receiving  an  object  into  awareness 
involves  additions,  involves  comparisons  similar  in  char 
acter  to  the  explanations  of  the  scientist.  One  does  not  even 
read  the  words  as  they  stand  on  the  printed  page,  but  must 
interpret  and  add  to  them  elements  not  seen,  which  from 
the  context  must  be  assumed  to  be  present.  At  the  same 
time  misprints  are  suppressed  and  ideas  are  supplied  in 
addition  to  the  words  or  to  take  the  place  of  words.  All  this 
is  probably  as  much  interpretation  as  inferring  the  presence 
of  copper  when  a  solution  turns  green,  and  it  is  only  a  more 
elaborate  interpretation  for  the  physicist  to  deduce  the 
size  of  atoms  from  markings  on  a  photographic  plate,  when 
X-rays  have  been  passed  through  a  given  crystal  before  they 
fall  upon  that  plate.  But  to  assert  that  one  cannot  distin 
guish  between  the  processes  involved  in  ordinary  percep 
tion,  the  processes  that  go  to  constitute  the  given,  and  the 
interpretations  that  are  made  of  the  given,  need  not  be  fatal 
to  the  view.  Our  statement  that  perception  is  made  up  of 
the  effects  of  immediate  stimuli,  plus  old  memories  and  other 
additions,  is  itself  a  psychological  interpretation,  not  an 
immediate  datum.  Each  interpretation  may  be  a  datum  for 
another  interpretation;  in  fact,  that  seems  essential  if  psy 
chological  or  logical  or  philosophical  investigations  are  to 
be  carried  out.  The  conclusion  reached  by  the  physicist  is 
a  datum  for  the  logician  who  is  seeking  to  understand  think 
ing,  in  the  same  way  that  the  immediate  appreciation  of 
matter  is  the  datum  for  the  physicist  or  chemist  who  reduces 
that  matter  to  atoms  or  ions.  The  explanation  of  one  mo 
ment  becomes  the  datum  of  the  next,  but  the  datum  is 
fundamentally  real  as  datum  rather  than  as  explanation. 
The  physicist  will  continue  to  think  as  he  does  whether  his 
thinking  does  or  does  not  accord  with  the  interpretations  of 
the  process  given  by  the  logician,  just  as  the  scientist  con 
tinues  to  see  colors  long  after  he  has  shown  that  they  are 
only  electro-magnetic  waves.  While  the  particular  element 


THE  DATUM  173 

in  experience  is  frequently  at  once  datum  and  interpretation, 
it  is  quite  easy  to  distinguish  the  function;  as  event  we  take 
one  attitude  towards  it  and  as  explanation  quite  another. 
It  is  always  real  and  true  as  datum,  while  as  explanation  it 
may  certainly  be  false  and  even  unreal. 

It  is  from  these  similarities  between  explanation  and 
datum  that  the  conclusion  has  been  drawn  on  the  one  hand 
that  the  datum  is  itself  the  result  of  inference,  and  on  the 
other  that  the  explanation  is  immediately  known.  The  one 
is  the  favorite  statement  of  the  idealist,  the  other  of  the 
realist.  Strictly  speaking  both  are  wrong,  since  to  reach  the 
conclusion  each  introduces  a  slight  difference  in  the  meaning 
of  the  middle  term  or  assumes  a  third  proposition  not  ex 
plicitly  present.  The  idealist  takes  it  for  granted  that  all 
explanation  of  the  immediate  stimulus  must  be  by  means  of 
transformation  into  ideas.  Since  all  must  be  interpreted  in 
order  to  become  known,  all  must  be  idea.  The  realist,  on 
the  contrary,  assumes,  as  we  have  seen,  that  the  datum  is 
immediately  known  but,  misled  by  the  frequency  of  the 
realistic  interpretation  in  popular  speech,  he  assumes  that 
it  is  known  as  things  outside  the  datum,  such  as  the  atoms 
or  ions  of  the  chemist  or  the  cells  of  the  biologist.  Each 
interpretation  has  justification  in  its  place,  but  obviously 
it  is  true  neither  that  all  interpretation  is  by  ideas,  as  the 
idealist  understands  the  term,  nor  that  the  realistic  inter 
pretation  of  the  datum  is  the  datum  itself. 

Were  there  space,  it  would  be  interesting  to  work  out  the 
relations  of  the  different  forms  of  interpretation,  the  anal 
ogies  that  make  them  plausible,  and  the  relative  probability 
of  each,  but  this  would  require  writing  a  system  of  philos 
ophy.  The  scope  of  the  present  paper  is  limited  to  the  sug 
gestion  that  the  philosophers  re-examine  their  premises  and 
make  them  square  with  the  fact  they  have  overlooked,  that 
the  datum  is  not  an  assumption  but  the  actual  experience, 
immediate  knowledge,  or  awareness,  that  this  is  the  measure 
of  the  truth  of  all  statements,  general  as  well  as  particular, 
of  axioms  and  general  principles,  as  well  as  of  immediate  ob 
servations.  To  take  this  point  of  view  does  not  change  the 


174  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

present  systems  except  in  so  far  as  it  makes  it  impossible 
to  be  dogmatic  and  makes  it  necessary  to  admit  that  many 
explanations  may,  nay  must,  be  given  of  each  phenomenon, 
and  that  the  sole  test  of  any  theory  or  system  is  not  the  in 
conceivability  of  the  opposite,  or  its  deduction  from  prem 
ises  which  all  have  assumed  to  be  true,  but  simply  whether 
or  not  the  theory  or  system  offers  a  convenient  way  of  inter 
preting  or  using  the  datum.  Usefulness  is  the  only  measure 
of  adequacy  and  adequacy  is  truth.  This  means  again  that 
any  interpretation  that  is  useful  is  justifiable,  and  does  not 
prevent, — what  we  find  in  fact, — the  acceptance  of  different 
theories  that  are  at  present  irreconcilable.  All  this  would  not 
in  the  least  change  the  actual  character  of  science  or  philos 
ophy,  but  it  would  make  for  less  dogmatism,  less  acrimony 
in  discussion,  less  conceited  intolerance  for  opponents  of  one's 
own  latest  fad  in  opinion.  Each  might  continue  with  full 
vigor  upon  his  own  experiments  in  interpretation  without 
bestowing  contempt  upon  his  fellow  worker  whose  stand 
point  reveals  a  slightly  different  vista. 


THE  LIMITS  OF  THE  PHYSICAL  * 
GRACE  ANDRUS  DE  LACUNA 

IT  is  a  familiar  reflection  that  the  classic  dichotomy  of 
physical  and  psychical  is  the  natural  result  of  that  vision  of 
the  universe  which  so  stirred  the  generation  of  Descartes, 
and  which  has  loomed  so  large  upon  the  horizon  of  all 
philosophic  thinkers  down  to  our  own  day, — the  mechanical 
theory  of  the  universe.  This  vision  had  its  birth  in  the  dis 
covery,  or  rather  the  analytical  isolation  by  physical  science, 
of  classes  of  phenomena  of  universal  occurrence,  and  the  de 
scription  of  these  in  universal  terms.  The  behavior  of  the 
falling  body,  of  the  evenly  swinging  pendulum,  of  the  re 
bounding  elastic  ball,  is  the  same  wherever  it  is  observed. 
And  there  seems  to  be  no  set  of  things  in  the  world,  no  class 
of  events,  no  nook  or  corner  of  the  universe,  which  is  beyond 
the  long  reach  of  physical  science.  Whatever  exists  or  oc 
curs  anywhere  apparently  falls  under  one  or  more  of  these 
*  cases'  or  universals  of  physical  science.  It  matters  not 
whether  this  vision  of  the  world  takes  the  form  of  an  intricate 
dance  of  atoms,  or  endless  transformations  of  energy,  or  the 
interplay  of  centers  of  force;  it  is  the  same  vision  and  its 
consequences  are  identical. 

For,  in  every  case,  the  harshness  of  the  vision  must  be  miti 
gated;  and  mitigated  it  always  has  been,  and  is,  by  the  pic 
turing  of  the  psychic  as  a  realm  antithetical.  The  sole  ideal 
limit  to  the  physical  has  always  been  sought  in  its  alleged 
opposite,  the  psychical.  Those  who  have  accepted  the  vision 
of  a  universal  mechanism  have  traced  alongside,  or  behind, 

1  This  paper  was  read  before  the  American  Philosophical  Association 
in  New  York,  December,  1916.  The  writer  gladly  avails  herself  of  the 
opportunity  to  publish  it  here  as  a  mark  of  her  esteem  for  Professor 
Creighton,  though  she  regrets  that  circumstances  made  it  impossible  to 
prepare  a  special  paper  for  this  volume. 


1 76  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  physical  universe  another  universe  of  the  psychic  to 
complete  it.  Those  to  whom  the  vision  has  been  abhorrent, 
and  who  have  stoutly  defended  to  the  last  the  little  domain 
of  living  beings  as  a  realm  where  physical  uniformities  are 
interrupted,  have  attributed  the  interruption  to  the  presence 
and  operation  of  a  spiritual  being.  For  even  vital  force  is  a 
vaguely  conceived  impulse,  subconscious,  but  continuous 
with  the  conscious. 

Among  modern  thinkers,  the  majority  of  whom,  on 
epistemological  grounds  of  one  sort  or  another,  deny  ultimate 
ontological  validity  to  the  distinction,  the  dichotomy  of 
physical  and  psychical  still  persists  in  spite  of  its  altered 
status.  No  epistemological  theory  since  Locke  has  accepted 
the  ontological  dualism  of  physical  and  psychical.  No  care 
ful  thinker  today  would  consider  the  dualism  as  a  possible 
basis  for  epistemological  inquiry.  Because,  then,  the  episte 
mological  theorist  has  been  convinced  that  the  distinction 
between  physical  and  psychical  is  not  ontologically  ultimate, 
it  has  ceased  seriously  to  trouble  him.  He  has  been  too 
deeply  interested  in  his  own  concerns  to  note  that  the  di 
chotomy  still  persists,  albeit  with  altered  status.  That  it  does 
persist  is  evidenced  by  the  fact  that  neither  Berkleyan  nor 
absolute  idealist  nor  even  pragmatist  has  succeeded  either 
in  avoiding  or  in  settling  the  classic  controversy  between 
interactionism  and  parallelism.  At  least,  prominent  repre 
sentatives  of  all  three  schools  have  expressed  themselves 
upon  the  issues  of  this  controversy  in  terms  which  Descartes 
might  have  used,  and  have  vigorously  defended  one  or  the 
other  alternative.  I  would  not  assert  that  none  of  these 
philosophic  systems  is  capable  of  affording  a  restatement  of 
the  problem  in  soluble  form;  I  merely  point  out  as  significant 
that  no  attempt  to  do  so  has  met  with  general  acceptance 
even  within  its  own  school. 

We  are  now  in  the  midst  of  a  new  and  widespread  revolt 
against  this  persistent  antithesis.  But  it  is  noteworthy  that 
a  majority  of  recent  formulations  of  the  mental  or  psychical 
have  defined  it  either  as  that  which  is  non-physical,  or  as  a 
special  class  of  the  physical.  In  a  word,  we  are  still  engaged 


THE  LIMITS  OF  THE  PHYSICAL  177 

in  the  old  enterprise  of  describing  the  mental  in  its  relation 
to  the  physical.  The  very  statement  of  the  problem  is  based 
on  the  presumption  that  there  is  some  systematic  connection 
between  the  two  classes  of  phenomena.  We  would  not  dis 
cuss  the  relation  of  physical  and  psychical  if  we  did  not  as 
sume  that  the  distinction  between  them  was  significant  and 
fruitful.  But  is  this  assumption  well  founded?  What  is  its 
genesis  and  upon  what  considerations  does  it  rest? 

The  classic  formulation  of  the  dualism  of  physical  and 
psychical,  we  have  observed,  was  consequent  upon  the  con 
ception  of  physical  uniformities  as  universal.  Just  because 
the  whole  natural  world  was  conceived  as  a  physical  world, 
determined  throughout  by  mechanical  laws,  it  became  im 
perative  to  relate  the  mental  to  this  world,  and  to  treat  this 
relationship  as  definitive.  Hence,  if  we  are  to  succeed  in  our 
revolt  against  this  dualism,  it  would  seem  at  least  advisable 
to  examine  its  historical  and  logical  foundations. 

Our  present  attitude  toward  the  mechanical  theory  is 
marked  by  two  apparently  opposed  tendencies.  The  first 
of  these  is  a  widespread  and,  I  venture  to  think,  growing 
conviction  of  the  wrong-headedness  of  those  who  point  to 
certain  organic  processes  and  functions,  and  say,  "These  are 
inexplicable  in  terms  of  physical  science  and  therefore  we 
must  resort  to  some  hypothesis  different  in  kind,  an  en- 
telechy,  or  soul."  It  has  proved  in  the  past  a  losing  game  to 
set  specific  limits  of  that  sort  to  the  possibilities  of  physical 
analysis.  Besides,  we  are  doubtful  of  the  fruitfulness  of 
explanation  in  terms  of  entelechies  or  souls.  We  may  be 
ready  to  admit  that  the  physical  explanation  of  organic  and 
nervous  processes  will  involve  modification  and  development 
of  the  concepts  and  theories  of  physical  science  itself,  just 
as  the  extension  of  physical  science  to  outlying  phenomena 
in  the  past  has  involved  reorganization  within  the  science. 
But  however  great  this  development  may  prove  to  be,  it 
will  be  a  continuous  development  of  the  science,  not  leading 
in  the  direction  of  entelechies  and  souls.  This  is  debatable 
ground,  I  am  well  aware,  and  perhaps  this  tendency  to  dis 
credit  the  enterprise  of  the  vitalist  and  the  animist  is  less 


1 78  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

widespread  than  my  own  predilections  lead  me  to  sup 
pose. 

However  that  may  be,  whether  or  not  we  believe  that 
limits  to  the  extent  of  physical  science  are  to  be  found  in 
certain  specific  processes  of  organisms,  we  do  all  of  us  be 
lieve,  tacitly  at  least,  that  there  are  limits  to  the  relevant 
and  significant  extension  of  physical  description  and  ex 
planation.  Is  the  German  army  a  physical  entity,  and  will 
its  future  triumph  or  defeat  be  describable  in  terms  of  trans 
formations  of  energy,  or  chemical  recombinations?  Or  if 
such  description  is  inadequate,  can  it  be  satisfactorily  eked 
out  with  descriptions  of  psychical  processes  going  on  in  the 
minds  of  officers  and  men?  Again,  is  the  commerce  of 
the  United  States  a  physical  phenomenon  describable  as  a 
set  of  complex  redistributions  in  time  and  space?  Or  are 
the  economic  laws  which  it  exemplifies  physical  uniformities  ? 
Or  if  not,  are  they  describable  as  psychological  uniformities? 
In  these,  and  a  host  of  cases  like  these,  we  have  passed  beyond 
the  legitimate  limits  of  physical  science.  But  it  is  not  be 
cause  we  find  here  exceptions  to  physical  laws,  or  a  breakdown 
of  physical  continuity  which  we  may  attribute  to  the  opera 
tion  of  a  mental  factor.  No,  the  actual  limit  to  the  physical 
is  not  the  psychical,  but  the  essential  irrelevancy  of  the 
physical  categories.  They  are  fundamentally  and  essentially 
inapplicable  to  a  wide  range  of  the  things  and  events  of 
common  life  and  of  science.  Nor  is  this  to  be  set  down  to  the 
relatively  undeveloped  state  of  the  sciences.  It  is  outgrown, 
doctrinaire  folly  to  suppose  that  the  future  development  of 
such  a  science  as  economics,  for  example,  will  result  in  the 
exhibition  of  its  phenomena  and  their  laws  as  special  cases 
of  physical  phenomena  and  physical  laws.  The  development 
of  economics  is  not  in  that  direction,  as  we  all  know,  nor  is 
such  an  outcome  an  actual  ideal. 

But  to  recognize  that  the  fruitful  and  significant  applica 
tion  of  the  physical  categories  is  thus  limited  is  not  enough. 
The  ancient  claim  of  the  mechanical  theory  to  universal 
sufficiency  must  be  directly  adjudicated.  The  source  of 
what  we  have  termed  its  fundamental  and  essential  in- 


THE  LIMITS  OF  THE  PHYSICAL  179 

applicability  must  be  exhibited.    For  the  vision  is  still  com 
pelling,  even  though  we  believe  it  illusory. 

If  we  consider  the  events  which  are  taking  place  in  the 
world  at  any  time,  from  a  great  historic  event,  such  as  the 
conflict  going  on  in  Europe,  to  our  own  recent  national 
election,  the  spread  and  subsidence  of  infantile  paralysis,  or 
even  your  yesterday's  conversation  with  a  friend,  all  these 
events  seem  resolvable  into  physical  occurrences.  Even  if 
it  be  maintained  that  many,  or  even  all,  of  these  events  were 
the  outcome  of  human  purposes,  nevertheless  the  purpose 
manifested  itself,  and  could  have  manifested  itself,  only  in 
physical  occurrences.  We  can  envisage  them  all,  and  con 
ceive  them  as  wholly  describable  down  to  the  last  detail,  as 
redistributions  of  mass  and  transformations  of  energy. 
Moreover  these  occurrences,  each  and  all,  have  their  places 
in  a  vast  interconnected  complex  of  such  processes,  stretching 
out  indefinitely  in  space  and  back  indefinitely  into  the  past. 
Unless  we  suppose  the  continuity  to  have  been  interrupted 
by  the  operation  of  psychic  factors,  we  conceive  each  item 
of  these  events,  such  as  the  discharge  of  a  projectile  from 
a  German  trench  or  the  dropping  of  a  marked  ballot  into 
the  ballot-box,  to  have  been  determined  by  antecedent 
physical  conditions.  We  thus  find  ourselves  involved  in  an 
apparent  antinomy.  On  the  one  hand,  it  seems  impossible  to 
admit  that  mechanical  explanation  is  ultimate  or  sufficient; 
on  the  other  hand,  it  seems  impossible  to  deny  it.  Perhaps 
it  will  help  us  to  escape  from  this  embarrassment,  if  we  take 
for  consideration  some  familiar  and  typical  concrete  ex 
ample:  the  recent  Democratic  victory. 

The  particular  event  which  occurred  last  November  is 
resolvable  into  a  vast  mass  of  occurrences,  such  as  the  going 
to  the  respective  polls  of  the  voters  all  over  the  country,  the 
marking  of  ballots,  the  subsequent  fall  of  the  ballots  into  the 
boxes,  etc.  And  each  of  these  occurrences  may  be  similarly 
broken  up,  until,  as  an  ideal  limit,  we  may  conceive  that 
whole  group  of  events  which  constituted  the  election  and 
the  Democratic  victory  as  a  multitude  of  redistributions  of 
mass  and  transformations  of  energy.  Every  detail  is  ac- 


l8o  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

counted  for,  nothing  is  omitted.  In  a  like  manner  we  may 
conceive  other  events  of  the  same  class,  Democratic  victories 
of  former  years,  described  in  detail  as  groups  of  physical 
occurrences. 

But  if  we  now  proceed  to  collate  and  compare  these  de 
scriptions  of  the  particular  cases,  in  order  to  formulate  a 
general  description,  we  find  that  they  present  no  character 
istic  identity.  If  they  were  not  already  given  as  belonging 
to  the  same  class,  we  should  never  be  led  by  our  physical 
analysis  to  class  them  together.  But  this  means  that  the 
phenomenon  ' Democratic  victory'  is  not  a  physical  event. 

Let  us  take  a  very  simple  analogy.  On  a  piece  of  squared 
canvas,  such  as  our  great-grandmothers  used  for  working 
samplers,  one  may  embroider  in  cross-stitch  all  sorts  of 
figures  by  filling  in  the  squares  in  rows  according  to  direc 
tions.  One  may,  for  instance,  embroider  a  series  of  figures 
of  dogs  of  different  kinds  and  in  different  poses.  Each  such 
figure  may  be  described  as  made  up  of  designated  squares  in 
designated  rows,  and  a  mathematical  formula  may  thus  be 
given  which  will  serve  as  a  description,  or  as  a  rule  for  mak 
ing  such  a  figure.  Similarly,  any  and  every  dog  which  it  is 
possible  to  embroider  may  be  so  described.  But  if  we  were 
asked  to  give  a  formula  for  dog  in  general,  which  would  serve 
as  a  general  rule  for  embroidering  dogs,  we  simply  could  not 
do  it.  The  common  property  which  all  figures  of  dogs  have 
is  not  to  be  found  by  such  an  analysis  of  structure,  for  it  is 
constituted  by  relationships  not  expressible  in  terms  of  or 
dered  and  numbered  squares. 

Similarly,  that  which  is  common  to  all  Democratic  vic 
tories  is  not  exhibited  by  an  analysis  of  each  such  event  into 
physical  occurrences.  Physical  science  does  not  yield  ade 
quate  principles  of  classification  for  the  articulation  of  our 
world. 

We  may  then,  in  part  at  least,  ascribe  our  contradictory 
attitudes  towards  the  claims  of  the  mechanical  theory  to 
the  confused  assumption  that  because  any  particular  thing 
or  event  may  be  described  in  physical  terms,  the  class  to 
which  it  belongs  may  also  be  so  described.  In  terms  of  logic, 


THE  LIMITS  OF  THE  PHYSICAL  181 

the  error  lies  in  failing  to  recognize  that  what  is  true  of  all 
the  members  taken  distributively  is  not  necessarily  true  of 
the  class  as  such. 

But  the  further  question  at  once  arises,  whether,  if  every 
particular  thing  or  event  in  the  world  is  completely  de- 
scribable  in  physical  terms,  we  must  not  after  all  admit  that 
the  claims  of  the  mechanical  theory  to  supremacy  are  valid? 
If  such  an  event  as  the  recent  Democratic  victory  is  re 
ducible  to  physical  occurrences,  is  it  not  wholly  determined 
by  physical  conditions?  How  can  there  be  room  for  any 
further  determination,  e.  g.,  by  social  conditions?  Must  not 
any  class  not  definable  by  physical  principles  be  merely 
fictitious?  Or,  if  we  insist  that  both  sorts  of  determination 
are  equally  valid,  are  we  not  committed  to  a  parallelism  more 
hopeless  than  the  alleged  psycho-physical  relation? 

Such  a  conclusion  seems  unavoidable  if  we  accept  the 
analysis  of  the  particular  event  into  physical  occurrences  as 
legitimate.  This  point  now  demands  closer  scrutiny.  The 
Democratic  victory  of  last  November  is  resolvable,  we  said, 
into  a  multitude  of  physical  occurrences.  But  when  so  re 
solved,  it  has  lost  all  claim  to  be  considered  as  a  single  event. 
It  is  not  even  a  complex  of  physical  occurrences,  for  the 
physical  occurrences  which  constitute  it  have  no  physical 
connection  with  each  other  except  via  the  whole  universe. 
From  the  standpoint  of  physical  science  the  selection  of  the 
scattered  occurrences  which  constitute  this  event  is  per 
fectly  arbitrary.  It  would  be  just  as  reasonable  to  group  to 
gether  the  falling  of  snowfiakes  over  the  mound  which  marks 
Scott's  grave  in  the  Antarctic,  the  spring  of  a  tiger  in  the 
jungles  of  Africa,  and  the  purchase  of  a  set  of  furs  by  the 
czarina  of  Russia,  and  call  them  an  event.  The  slipping  a 
dollar  into  the  hand  of  a  negro  voter  in  Ohio  and  the  marking 
of  a  ballot  in  California  have  no  more  physical  connection 
than  the  former  events.  Physically  speaking,  your  marking 
your  ballot  is  far  more  directly  determined  by  the  tempera 
ture  of  the  atmosphere  than  it  is  by  the  war  in  Europe,  while 
its  relation  to  the  cerebral  structure  of  Mr.  Hughes  or  Mr. 
Wilson  is  altogether  negligible.  No,  what  we  said  before  of 


1 82  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  class  'Democratic  victory,'  that  it  was  not  a  physical 
phenomenon,  we  must  now  say  of  the  particular  event  which 
took  place  in  November.  It,  too,  is  no  physical  event,  either 
simple  or  complex.  And  to  our  previous  generalization,  that 
physical  science  does  not  yield  adequate  principles  of  classi 
fication  for  the  articulation  of  our  world,  we  must  now  add 
that  it  does  not  yield  adequate  principles  of  individuation 
for  the  furnishing  of  our  world.  For  physical  science  there 
are  neither  German  armies  nor  Democratic  victories,  neither 
cabbages  nor  kings.  To  speak  of  such  a  thing  or  event  as 
being  mechanically  determined  is  to  talk  nonsense. 

We  must  not  forget  that  the  sciences,  and  above  all  the 
physical  sciences,  deal  only  with  the  abstract.  The  phe 
nomena  of  science  are  universals,  and  it  can  take  cognizance 
of  the  particular  only  in  so  far  as  the  particular  presents  itself 
as  a  case  of  the  universal  phenomenon.  The  concrete  particu 
lar  event  which  we  designate  'the  dropping  of  your  ballot 
into  the  ballot  box'  may  be  dealt  with  by  physical  science 
in  so  far  as  it  is  considered  a  case  of  a  falling  body,  or  a  case 
of  degradation  of  energy,  but  as  that  concrete  particular, 
standing  in  an  indefinite  complex  of  relationships,  it  is  not 
to  be  exhausted  by  physical  analysis  any  more  than  it  is  by 
any  other  sort  of  scientific  analysis.  Similarly,  what  science 
can  exhibit  as  determined  is  always  the  particular  case  of 
some  universal  phenomenon,  the  abstract  particular,  and 
not  the  concrete  particular.  As  a  'falling  body'  the  drop 
ping  of  your  ballot  may  be  exhibited  as  an  event  determined 
by  the  masses  and  distance  from  each  other  of  the  piece  of 
paper  and  the  earth,  but  as  a  concrete,  particular  occurrence 
it  cannot  be  exhibited  as  determined.  The  attempt  to  con 
ceive  it  as  determined,  even  ideally,  involves  a  resort  to  the 
whole  universe.  One  might  as  well  resort  to  the  Deity  as  an 
explanation.  What  must  be  conceived  as  determined  by  the 
universe  is,  for  purposes  of  scientific  description  and  ex 
planation,  indeterminate. 

To  sum  up  the  argument:  The  traditional  assumption  that 
the  limits  to  the  physical  are  to  be  found  exclusively  in  the 
psychical  is  not  well  founded.  On  the  contrary,  the  limits 


THE  LIMITS  OF  THE  PHYSICAL  183 

to  the  physical  description  and  explanation  of  the  things  and 
events  of  common  life  and  of  science  are  set  by  the  intelligible 
applicability  of  the  concepts  of  physical  science  to  such  de 
scription,  and  of  the  laws  of  physical  science  to  such  ex 
planation.  This  is  not  to  be  determined  a  priori  by  meta 
physical  considerations,  but  empirically.  In  general  it  may 
be  said  that  phenomena  are  legitimately  to  be  considered  as 
physical  only  if  the  principles  of  their  individuation  and 
classification  can  be  stated  in  physical  terms. 

The  problem  of  the  relation  of  physical  and  psychical  is 
thus  seen  to  be  not  a  metaphysical  problem,  since  there  is 
no  ontological  dualism.  Furthermore,  we  have  no  ground 
for  the  presumption  that  there  is  any  systematic  relationship 
of  the  one  to  the  other  such  that  the  psychical  is  most  fruit 
fully  to  be  defined  in  its  relation  to  the  physical.  The 
specific  problem  of  the  relation  of  the  psychical  to  bodily 
behavior  (the  discussion  of  which  cannot  be  undertaken  in 
the  limits  of  this  paper)  thus  presents  itself  freed  from  meta 
physical  implications.  The  question  which  we  have  to  ask 
(and  it  is  a  question  whose  importance  I  believe  it  would  be 
difficult  to  exaggerate)  is :  Is  the  behavior  of  organisms,  and 
in  particular  of  organisms  with  nervous  systems,  a  physical 
phenomenon?  Are  the  characteristic  phenomena  which  it 
presents,  and  the  characteristic  uniformities  which  these  ex 
hibit,  capable  of  description  in  terms  of  physical  science? 
More  particularly,  is  it  fruitful,  or  even  possible,  to  describe 
in  physical  terms  those  characteristic  modes  of  behavior 
which  we  by  common  consent  associate  with  distinctively 
psychical  processes,  such  as  instinct,  emotion,  perception, 
and  the  rest?  If  it  is  not,  if  such  uniformities  of  behavior 
are  not  describable  as  physical  uniformities,  then  the  mind- 
body  relation  is  not  properly  speaking  a  psycho-physical  re 
lationship,  and  the  problem  of  the  relation  of  the  psychical 
to  the  physical,  like  many  another  problem  with  which 
philosophy  has  long  struggled,  has  no  determinate  solution. 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL? 
HENRY  WILKES  WRIGHT 

IT  is  a  common  reproach  flung  at  philosophers  that  they 
only  renew  from  generation  to  generation  the  ancient  con 
troversy  between  idealism  and  materialism.  And  the  candid 
philosopher  is  constrained  to  admit  that  appearances  go  far 
to  justify  the  charge.  The  history  of  philosophy  records  a 
genuine  progress  in  the  solution  of  philosophical  problems; 
there  can  be  no  doubt  of  that.  This  progress  consists,  how 
ever,  in  making  each  of  the  two  conflicting  views  less  one 
sided  and  more  adequate  to  the  facts;  it  does  not  remove 
the  deep-seated  cause  of  their  antagonism  nor  unite  them  in 
a  lasting  synthesis.  The  controversy  is  ever  renewed,  only 
on  higher  ground.  Idealism  forswears  subjectivity,  becomes 
'objective,'  and  gains  a  precarious  supremacy  which  it 
maintains  more  or  less  successfully  through  the  vicissitudes 
of  a  century.  But  its  inherent  inadequacy  provokes  the 
inevitable  reaction.  Materialism,  laid  away  with  many  an 
eloquent  funeral  oration,  reappears  upon  the  scene,  very  full 
of  life  and  flushed  with  youthful  enthusiasm.  But  now  it 
appears  in  the  guise  of  realism  and  through  its  deference  to 
logical  forms  and  processes  pays  tribute  to  the  power  and 
potency  of  thought. 

It  is  my  wish  to  show,  first,  that  the  opposition  between 
materialism  and  idealism  is  rooted  deep  in  human  experience; 
second,  that  intelligence  furnishes  no  category  already  formu 
lated  which  is  able  to  reconcile  teleology  and  mechanism; 
and,  third,  that  it  is  only  through  a  study  of  man's  social 
development  and  cultural  achievements  that  we  can  hope  to 
discover  such  a  principle  of  synthesis. 

Nothing  that  is  experienced  is  alien  to  philosophy.  The 
sole  qualification  which  an  object  must  possess  in  order  to 
become  subject-matter  for  philosophical  investigation  is 
that  it  be  experienced.  The  experience  in  question  is  primar- 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          185 

ily  the  universal  experience  of  mankind;  experiences  peculiar 
to  individuals  are  not  excluded,  to  be  sure,  but  they  must 
bear  some  relation  to  human  experience  in  general  if  they  are 
to  be  even  intelligible  as  material  for  study.  If  the  student 
of  philosophy  assumes,  in  order  to  gain  for  his  conclusions 
the  kind  of  objectivity  possessed  by  the  principles  of  natural 
science,  that  everything  real  exists  in  mathematically  deter- 
minable  relations  or  that  all  behavior  takes  the  form  of  re 
sponse  to  external  stimulation,  he  defeats  the  purpose  of 
his  philosophizing  at  the  very  beginning.  For  he  begins 
with  an  assumption  in  regard  to  the  subject-matter  of  his 
investigation  that  denies  to  the  sciences  of  value  due  con 
sideration;  thus  he  pre-judges  the  whole  philosophic  problem 
at  the  start  and  condemns  his  own  conclusions  to  one- 
sidedness  and  inadequacy.  Such  well-intended  but  ill-judged 
efforts  to  make  philosophy  'objective'  in  the  narrower  sense 
commit  the  unforgivable  sin,  philosophically  speaking,  of  ac 
cepting  without  criticism  the  principles  and  presuppositions 
of  natural  science,  when  it  is  the  first  and  primary  task  of 
philosophy  to  subject  these  to  analysis  and  criticism,  to 
criticise  in  fact  all  the  categories  of  experience.1 

We  begin,  therefore,  with  experienced  objects.  These,  we 
find,  fall  into  two  classes  according  to  their  characteristic 
mode  of  activity.  To  the  first  class  belong  all  the  objects 
whose  activity  is  determined  by  other  objects,  is  externally 
determined.  This  class  includes  the  objects  which  make  up 
the  so-called  physical  world.  The  movement  of  each  of  these 
is  circumscribed  and  delimited  by  the  movement  of  all  the 
other  objects  embraced  in  the  system.  Into  a  second  class 
fall  all  those  objects  whose  activity  is  ^//-determined,  i.  e., 
determined  by  their  own  intrinsic  potencies  of  development 
and  self-expression.  The  "intrinsic  potencies"  of  an  object 
are  the  powers  or  capacities  which  are  peculiar  to  it  and 
render  its  behavior  in  some  measure  unique.  Their  char 
acter  is,  moreover,  fully  revealed  only  in  actual  expression 
and  cannot  be  fully  foreknown  or  predicted  on  the  basis  of 

1  Cf.  Professor  Creighton,  "The  Copernican  Revolution  in  Philosophy," 
Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XXII,  1913,  p.  139. 


1 86  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

previous  performances  of  the  object  itself  or  any  other 
agency.  To  this  class  belong  living  organisms,  conscious 
individuals,  free  persons.  Of  course  this  difference  in  modes 
of  determination  does  not  divide  the  objects  of  experience 
into  two  entirely  separate  groups:  many  are  subject  to,  or 
seem  capable  of,  both  kinds  of  determination.  Thus  the 
living  individual  as  a  physical  object  is  subject  to  external 
determination,  while  physical  agencies  do,  on  their  part,  occa 
sionally  manifest  unsuspected  capacities  for  self-development 
and  individuation  (as  must  have  been  the  case  when  life 
originated  on  this  planet).  But  these  complications  are, 
comparatively  speaking,  superficial;  the  distinction  between 
the  mechanical  and  the  teleological  goes  to  the  very  root  of 
our  experience,  cleaving  it  in  twain  and  supplying  an  essen 
tial  principle  for  dividing  its  objects. 

As  this  distinction  between  external  determination  and 
self-determination  underlies  all  other  distinctions,  the  ques 
tion  next  occurs,  What  is  our  original  experience  of  each  of 
these  kinds  of  determination?  Our  original  experience  of 
external  determination  is  given,  it  would  appear,  in  our 
efforts  to  move  our  own  bodies  in  spite  of  the  resistance  of 
fered  by  objects  external  to  them.  And  our  original  expe 
rience  of  self-determination  seems  to  come  in  the  direction 
which  we,  through  the  choosing  of  ends,  give  to  our  bodily 
movement.  Now  it  is  a  remarkable  fact  that  both  of  these 
root-experiences  unite  in  the  experience  of  voluntary  action. 
Indeed,  they  do  in  their  unity  constitute  this  experience: 
voluntary  action  is  the  attainment,  through  external  ad 
justment,  of  ends  which  as  chosen  express  the  intrinsic  capac 
ities  of  the  agent.  Since  volition  occupies  this  central  posi 
tion  in  our  experience,  it  is  not  unreasonable  to  expect  that 
a  thorough-going  analysis  of  its  activity  will  bring  us  into 
touch  with  fundamental  realities  and  thus  open  the  way  to 
a  solution  of  the  problem  of  the  mental  versus  the  material. 

Let  us  therefore  find  out  if  we  can  what  powers  or  capac 
ities  are  regularly  employed  in  voluntary  action,  what  is 
their  method  of  operation,  and  what  are  the  conditions  under 
which  they  work. 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          187 

The  first  capacity  that  comes  into  play  in  the  regular 
working  of  will  is  ideation  (or  free  imagination).  We  com 
monly  say  that  the  power  of  will  is  first  shown  in  the  choice 
of  an  end.  By  this  we  mean  that  volition  is  able  to  imagine 
qualities  or  groups  of  qualities  which  are  possible  of  realiza 
tion.  By  identifying  itself  with  these  ideal  qualities  rather 
than  with  those  which  are  actually  present,  the  will  projects 
the  course  of  its  own  future  activity.  The  ideal  qualities  in 
question,  which  become  ends  of  future  action  and  sources  of 
future  satisfaction,  are  themselves  universals,  inasmuch  as 
they  retain  their  characteristic  meaning  through  changing 
experiences  of  choice,  pursuit,  and  realization.  They  do, 
as  a  matter  of  fact,  give  expression  to  the  self-identity  of 
volition,  maintained  through  a  succession  of  changing  acts. 

The  second  factor  essential  to  the  working  of  will  is  the 
capacity  for  effort.  As  long  as  the  end  of  action  remains  a 
mere  possibility,  it  is  opposed  to  the  actual  situation  of  the 
agent  with  its  existing  opportunities  for  self-realization.  If 
the  end  is  to  be  realized,  the  actual  situation  of  the  agent 
must  be  altered.  Such  readjustment  of  existing  conditions 
requires  effort,  since  objective  reality  resists  readjustment 
or  transformation.  This  resistance  is  encountered  by  the 
agent  at  one  point,  at  several  points  simultaneously,  or  in 
succession  at  the  same  point  or  at  several  points.  Hence 
the  responding  effort  takes  the  form  of  movement  having 
three  parameters,  or  occurring  in  tri-dimensional  space. 
These  movements,  since  their  character  is  objectively  de 
termined,  are  particular  events  occurring  at  certain  times 
and  (in  relation  to  other  movements)  certain  places;  they 
are  particular  episodes  in  the  life-history  of  individual  or 
ganisms. 

The  realization  of  the  ideal  objective  constitutes  the  third 
moment  in  the  operation  of  volition.  The  chosen  end  is 
realized  when  the  voluntary  agent  through  his  own  effortful 
movement  so  alters  existing  conditions  that  the  movements 
at  his  command  are  such  as  no  longer  to  thwart  or  exclude, 
but  rather  to  sustain,  reinforce,  and  intensify  the  qualities 
he  desires  to  experience.  Thus  the  ideal  end  is  brought  into 


1 88  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

dynamic  continuity  with  the  system  of  motor  co-ordinations 
established  by  the  agent;  its  distinctive  qualities  may  be 
re-experienced  at  will;  it  thus  becomes  a  permanent,  a  real, 
means  of  self-expression,  and  may  constitute  the  starting- 
point  for  new  activities. 

We  have  discovered  the  two  agencies  which  underlie  the 
operation  of  volition  and  determine  the  character  of  its  ac 
tivity.  The  first  is  the  subjective  principle,  the  will  itself, 
an  originating  source  of  self-directed  activity.  The  second 
is  the  objective  factor,  having  a  reality  equally  underived  and 
original,  which  limits  the  range  of  voluntary  activity,  some 
times  checking  and  thwarting  it  and  at  others  permitting 
its  expression  along  chosen  lines. 

The  two  agencies,  subjective  and  objective,  whose  ex 
istence  is  implied  in  all  voluntary  action,  have  been  taken 
abstractly  and,  when  thus  treated,  appear  as  purely  formal 
principles.  They  do  not,  when  thus  understood  in  terms  of 
their  general  character  and  distinctive  function,  furnish  any 
explanation  of  the  content  or  material  of  the  existing  world. 
It  is  not  as  formal  principles,  however,  that  these  two 
agencies  appear  in  our  actual  experience.  There  we  always 
find  them  working  with,  or  upon,  a  body  of  material.  Our 
constructive  imagination  in  the  choice  of  ends  unites  qualities 
in  varying  combinations,  but  the  qualities  themselves  are 
presupposed;  we  essay  and  effect  different  co-ordinations  of 
movement,  but  the  species  of  movement  we  co-ordinate  are 
themselves  given  as  original  endowment.  The  philosophical 
thinker  who  is  interested  in  explaining  the  facts  of  experience 
by  a  few  fundamental  principles  is  tempted  to  deduce  or 
derive,  if  he  can,  the  actual  content  of  experience  from  its 
formal  principles,  but  such  attempts  can  be  given  the  ap 
pearance  of  success  only  through  a  logical  legerdemain 
which  is  as  disastrous  to  the  philosophy  perpetrating  it  as 
it  is  sophistical  in  itself.  Renouncing  any  such  mistaken 
ambition,  therefore,  and  accepting  the  content  of  experience 
as  given  along  with  its  formal  principles,  we  must  indicate 
the  material  with  which  volition  works  in  its  choices  and 
its  actions. 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          189 

The  qualities  that  constitute  the  object-material  with 
which  our  imagination  works  in  the  formulation  of  ends  are 
given  in  a  system  of  original  interests.  (These  interests  we 
usually  think  of  as  the  outcome  of  actions  performed  before 
the  advent  of  volition  under  the  influence  of  instincts  which 
have  been  developed  in  man  or  the  lower  animals  by  natural 
selection.  Since,  however,  the  relation  of  stimulus  to  re 
sponse  is  itself  a  category  of  intelligence  and  all  thinking  is 
an  expression  of  will,  such  explanations  are  subject  to  the 
reservation  that  they  all  presuppose  will  as  the  fundamental 
activity  of  human  experience  and  hence  cannot  possibly 
reduce  it  to  a  negative  or  derivative  status.)  The  interests 
in  question  are  ends  or  objects  of  established  value.  They 
represent  permanent  prospects  of  satisfaction,  each  within 
the  limits  of  its  own  content  offering  to  volition  a  reliable 
opportunity  for  free  self-expression.  In  idea  they  mean  a 
variety  of  existing  objects  necessary  for  man's  physical  se 
curity  and  comfort,  such  as  articles  of  food  and  drink,  ma 
terials  for  clothing,  places  of  shelter,  sources  of  parental  and 
sexual  and  social  satisfaction.  All  these  interests  are  com 
binations  of  qualities,  the  same  qualities  being  components 
of  different  interests.  The  qualities  (identical  with  the 
familiar  sense-qualities,  primary  and  secondary)  are  uni- 
versals  and,  entering  themselves  into  different  combinations, 
bind  the  totality  of  interests  into  a  system.  Of  course  the 
interests  under  consideration  are  not  to  be  understood  as  a 
limited  number  of  ready-made  and  unchangeable  alterna 
tives  to  which  the  choice  of  human  agents  is  limited.  They 
do  offer  such  ready-made  alternatives  in  the  way  of  guaran 
teed  satisfaction,  but  they  offer  much  more,  inasmuch  as 
they  are  severally  capable  of  analysis  and  recombination  to 
an  unlimited  extent,  thus  opening  to  the  choice  of  the  agent 
an  indefinite  number  of  new  ends  whose  possibilities  he  may 
at  will  explore  by  action. 

The  qualities  which  enter  as  constituents  into  the  original 
interests  are  easily  distinguishable  into  a  few  main  classes. 
First,  and  in  the  beginning  most  important  because  of  the 
promise  they  hold  forth  of  immediate  satisfaction,  are  those 


190  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

qualities  which  we,  in  the  language  of  psychology,  call  tactual 
and  organic.  Such  are, — to  take  random  instances, — the 
taste  and  savour  of  nourishing  food,  the  satiety  which  follows 
eating,  the  softness  and  warmth  of  firm,  flexible  clothing,  the 
vital  exaltation  of  victorious  combat,  the  pressure  of  friendly 
hand-clasp,  the  thrill  of  sexual  contact.  The  second  class 
of  qualities  is  kinaesthetic.  Images  and  ideas  of  the  move 
ments  required  to  approach  with  the  body  or  follow  with 
the  eye  the  source  of  expected  organic  satisfaction  are  closely 
associated  with  the  ideas  of  such  satisfactions.  In  addition 
to  these  two  classes  of  qualities  there  are  two  others  which 
originally  seem  to  serve  as  signs  of  their  presence  or  guides 
to  their  realization:  ideas  of  colors  and  of  sounds.  Color 
with  its  many  hues  and  shades  possesses  interest  primarily 
because  it  identifies  objects  as  offering  specific  satisfactions 
and  indicates  the  sequence  of  movements  that  must  be  made 
to  approach  them.  Auditory  images,  particularly  ideas  of 
spoken  words,  are  connected  with  the  objects  that  appeal 
as  ends  of  action  and  signify  either  their  location  or  their 
value  or  both. 

Turning  now  from  imagined  ends  to  the  motor  adjustments 
by  which  they  are  realized,  we  find  that  the  movements  pos 
sible  to  man  as  a  voluntary  agent  fall  into  a  few  general 
classes.  There  are  first  the  movements  of  the  whole  body, 
trunk  and  limbs,  as  it  changes  its  position  relative  to  other 
objects,  and  grasps,  holds,  or  otherwise  manipulates  or  moves 
them.  In  a  second  class  are  the  movements  involved  in  ad 
justing  the  sensory  apparatus,  primarily  that  of  sight  and 
hearing.  Stationary  objects  are  fixated  and  surveyed,  mov 
ing  objects  are  followed,  their  changes  being  compensated  by 
readjustments  of  the  visual  mechanism.  Into  a  third  class 
fall  the  movements  of  the  vocal  apparatus  in  speech,  by 
which  the  human  individual  communicates  to  others  his 
experiences  of  pursuit  and  satisfaction  and  by  this  means 
influences  their  behavior. 

The  fact  that  a  system  of  interests  and  a  capacity  for 
movements  such  as  have  just  been  described  are  given  along 
with  the  power  of  volition  itself  has  important  implications 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          191 

which  must  now  be  made  clear.  The  existence  of  the  afore 
said  interests  and  capacity  for  movement  implies  the  ex 
istence  along  with  volition  of  a  world  of  sense-objects  and  a 
society  of  free  agents. 

The  original  interests  from  which  man  selects  his  ends  of 
action  are  at  once  plans  of  movement  and  promises  of  sat 
isfaction.  Since  all  movements  are  of  the  tri-dimensional 
order,  and  identical  qualities  are  present  in  different  com 
plexes,  it  is  evident  that  all  movements  fall  within  one  space 
and  all  qualities  are  included  within  one  teleological  system. 
Hence  an  extended  world  containing  a  multiplicity  of  objects 
of  different  kinds  may  be  taken  for  a  pre-condition  of  any 
voluntary  action  whatsoever.  But  the  world  of  sense-objects 
as  actually  perceived  depends  for  its  character  and  ar 
rangement  upon  the  motor  adjustments  of  the  perceiving 
individual.  Such  motor  adjustment,  usually  of  the  visual  ap 
paratus  of  the  agent,  signifies  the  presence  of  expected  qual 
ities  (of  color,  form,  figure,  etc.)  and  in  some  measure  locates 
the  object.  The  results  of  such  visual  adjustment  are  con 
firmed  by  bodily  movements  towards  or  away  from  per 
ceived  objects,  accompanied  by  a  visual  readjustment  to 
compensate  for  shifting  of  objects  in  altering  perspective. 
The  arrangement  of  objects  in  the  sense-world  depends  upon 
the  individual  point-of-view  and  changes  with  every  change 
of  individual  position.  The  order  of  these  changes  is  noted 
and  remembered  by  the  individual,  is  compared  with  the 
experiences  of  others  who  themselves  figure  in  the  changing 
panorama  and  with  whom  the  individual  is  in  constant  com 
munication,  and  thus  a  system  of  spatial  relations  is  pro 
jected  whose  objectivity  is  generally  acknowledged. 

The  voluntary  agent  is  not  merely  capable  of  movement 
under  the  limitations  imposed  by  objective  reality,  he  is 
also  capable  of  determining  his  own  activity  by  a  free  choice 
among  ends.  These  ends  are,  as  we  have  seen,  universals; 
they  are  possible  modes  of  activity  which  promise  to  yield 
their  specific  satisfactions  whenever  engaged  in.  They  re 
tain  their  value  and  significance  as  long  as  the  voluntary 
agent  retains  his  identity;  their  universality  is  in  fact  an 


192  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

expression  of  the  identity  of  the  voluntary  agent  as  a  self- 
determining  center  or  source  of  activity.  Now  the  recog 
nition  by  a  number  of  individuals  of  the  same  system  of 
permanent  values  would  constitute  them  a  society  of  free 
persons.  It  has  been  pointed  out  that  the  interests  of  which 
the  human  individual  finds  himself  possessed  imply  the  ex 
istence  of  other  individuals  and  that  any  action  on  his  part 
in  fulfillment  of  these  interests  involves  the  perception  of 
such  others  as  objects  in  the  physical  world.  The  original 
interests,  moreover,  come  to  the  human  agent  in  association 
with  words.  Such  articulate  sounds  serve  to  symbolize  the 
identical  meaning  possessed  by  a  number  of  particular  ob 
jects  or  experiences  and  their  use  for  this  purpose  would  be 
impossible  apart  from  the  ability  to  appreciate  permanent 
meanings  and  values.  But  the  human  individual  is  not  left 
to  manufacture  his  own  stock  of  words  to  serve  as  signs  of 
universals;  he  receives  them  ready-made  as  a  part  of  his 
social  heredity.  Such  a  system  of  verbal  symbols  as  the 
human  individual  finds  in  existence  and  use  implies  the 
existence  of  a  number  of  others  recognizing  identical  mean 
ings  and  pursuing  common  ends.  The  original  conditions  of 
action,  therefore,  constitute  the  human  individual  a  member 
of  a  society  of  free  agents;  his  will  is  a  social  will  from  the 
start. 

Volition  thus  proves  to  be  the  key  to  the  structure  of  the 
experienced  world;  an  analysis  of  its  activity  brings  to  light 
the  determining  factors  of  human  experience.  The  first  of 
these  real  agencies  is  the  human  will  itself,  endowed  with  the 
power  of  directing  its  own  activity  and  of  effort  in  extending 
the  range  of  its  free  choice.  The  second  is  objective  reality, 
which  limits  and  circumscribes  the  action  of  the  will.  The 
material  of  human  choice  is  given,  furthermore,  as  a  variety 
of  sensory  qualities,  and  the  components  of  human  action 
as  a  system  of  motor  co-ordinations.  Volition,  in  so  far  as 
we  have  experience  of  its  powers,  operates  through  a  multi 
tude  of  individual  wills;  these  wills,  moreover,  act  in  a 
common  world  of  sense-objects  and  are  in  verbal  communica 
tion  with  each  other.  The  aim  of  will  is  its  own  development 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          193 

as  a  self-determining  agency;  it  seeks  to  enlarge  the  scope  of 
its  own  free  activity  by  increasing  the  number  and  variety 
of  objects  which  it  may  at  choice  experience.  The  opportu 
nities  for  choice  among  possible  ends  of  pursuit  are  practically 
limitless.  But  such  unlimited  choice  among  ideal  possibil 
ities  does  not  constitute  real  self-expression  for  will,  since 
ideas  are  realized  only  when  brought  into  harmony  with  the 
motor  adjustments  of  human  individuals.  Volition  seeks  to 
increase  the  variety  of  objects  whose  reality  is  thus  open  to 
its  experiencing;  it  does  this  in  actual  practice  by  endeavor 
ing  through  the  effort  of  motor  adjustment  to  realize  those 
ends  which,  when  they  are  realized,  open  to  the  choice  of 
the  agent  the  richest  content  of  qualities,  the  most  diverse 
detail  of  activities. 

Have  we  gained  from  our  analysis  of  experience  in  terms 
of  will  any  hint  of  a  solution  for  the  problem  of  the  dualism 
of  mind  and  matter?  Our  results  thus  far  seem  rather  to 
confirm  than  to  remove  the  opposition  in  question.  Ex 
perience  proves  to  have  its  source  in  the  action  of  two 
antagonistic  principles  or  agencies,  the  subjective  principle 
being  a  self-determining  activity  and  the  objective  factor 
setting  limits  to  its  free  play.  The  world  of  objects  as  we 
know  it  is  a  joint  product  of  these  two  agencies.  The  ob 
jective  factor  supplies  none  of  the  qualities  which  enter  into 
its  constitution  unless,  indeed,  we  suppose  that  the  system 
of  interests,  given  along  with  volition  and  containing  all  the 
qualities  predicated  of  existence,  comes  originally  from  ob 
jective  reality.1  Objective  reality  does,  however,  determine 
the  order  and  arrangement  which  these  qualities  have  in  the 
existing  world.  It  does  this  through  the  control  which  it 
exercises  over  the  action  of  voluntary  agents,  performed 
under  the  guidance  of  ideas  adopted  as  ends.  When  the 
attempted  motor  adjustments  are  hindered  or  prevented, 
the  idea  which  governs  the  action  as  a  working  hypothesis  is 
proved  false  and  its  hypothetical  object  non-existent.  When, 
on  the  contrary,  the  action  which  is  expected  to  revive  and 

1  This  subject  is  more  fully  discussed  by  the  writer  in  an  article,  "The 
Principles  of  Voluntarism,"  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XXIV,  1915,  p.  297. 


194  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

intensify  the  chosen  qualities  is  permitted  to  proceed  un 
hindered  to  its  intended  outcome,  the  idea  is  (as  we  say) 
realized;  its  constituent  qualities  are  given  objectivity. 
Since  rational  will  and  objective  reality  thus  co-operate  in 
the  production  of  the  experienced  world,  it  is  in  a  certain 
sense  itself  a  synthesis  of  mind  and  matter.  But  how  does 
it  unite  self-determination  and  externality?  Do  we  find  any 
relation  established  among  its  objects  which  stands  as  a 
genuine  reconciliation  of  teleology  and  mechanism?  At  this 
juncture  it  will  be  well  to  remind  ourselves  that  the  question 
of  a  synthetic  principle  capable  of  reconciling  the  categories 
of  teleology  and  mechanism  is  an  intellectual  one.  Now 
thought  is  itself  an  expression  of  will;  hence  its  activity  is 
subject  to  explanation  in  terms  of  the  voluntaristic  prin 
ciples  just  formulated.  The  bearing  of  these  principles  upon 
the  mind-matter  dualism  can  be  fully  understood  only  if 
we  first  determine  the  part  played  by  thought  in  the  compre 
hensive  activity  of  volition  and  also  consider  how  the  op 
posing  categories  of  teleology  and  mechanism  have  come  to 
conscious  recognition  in  the  course  of  intellectual  develop 
ment. 

The  power  of  ideation  has  been  shown  to  be  a  necessary 
factor  in  volition,  its  function  being  freely  to  imagine  objects 
as  ends  of  choice  and  pursuit.  The  faculty  of  thought  is  a 
development  of  this  original  capacity  for  ideation;  as  a  spe 
cialized  form  of  voluntary  action,  it  has  its  characteristic  aim 
and  distinctive  technique.  The  aim  of  thought  is  to  discover 
truth,  that  is,  to  formulate  in  an  ideal  system  all  objects  that 
can  be  realized.  As  an  authentic  expression  of  will  it  ex 
hibits,  under  its  own  distinctive  form,  the  three  essential 
moments  of  ideation,  effort,  and  realization.  Since  the 
thought-object  or  idea  is  primarily  an  end  of  action,  its 
validity  is  tested  by  the  results  of  action.1  The  true  idea  is 
the  idea  that  can  by  effortful  movement  be  brought  into 
such  dynamic  continuity  with  the  established  motor  ad 
justments  of  the  agent  that  it  can  be  re-experienced  at 

JC/.   H.   W.   Wright,   "Practical  Success  as  a  Criterion   of  Truth," 
Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XXII,  1913,  p.  606. 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          195 

will  and  made  the  starting-point  for  new  courses  of  ac 
tion. 

In  perception  the  distinctive  character  of  the  cognitive  or 
intellectual  first  declares  itself.  The  perceived  object  is  an 
end  of  action,  to  be  sure;  better,  it  is  a  plan  of  action  involv 
ing  an  anticipation  of  motor  adjustment  and  a  promise  of 
satisfaction.  Such  a  perception  is,  moreover,  verified  through 
action  and  by  the  results  of  action.  But  the  movements  by 
which  the  perception  is  verified  are  not  ordinarily  those 
which  are  anticipated  in  its  meaning,  nor  are  its  qualities 
the  results  desired.  The  movements  represented  in  the  per 
ception  are  primarily  those  of  the  whole  body  in  appropriat 
ing  the  object,  while  the  satisfactions  are  those  expected 
when  it  is  put  to  the  use  for  which  it  is  intended.  The  move 
ments  instantly  evoked  by  the  initial  interpretation,  however, 
are  adjustments  of  the  sensory  apparatus  (usually  of  sight 
and  hearing),  suited  to  prove  the  existence  of  qualities  in 
the  object  (for  the  most  part,  colors  and  sounds)  whose 
presence  guarantees,  in  advance  of  more  extensive  move 
ment,  that  the  results  desired  will  follow  when  these  latter 
movements  are  made.  The  perception  qua  perception  gains 
objectivity  when  the  sensory  adjustment  which  it  prompts  is 
permitted  to  proceed  unhindered  and  intelligence  is  stimu 
lated  thereby  to  fill  out  and  complete  the  interpretation 
which  evoked  it.  The  world  of  perception  is  a  world  of  ma 
terial  objects  externally  related  to  one  another  and  to  the 
body  of  the  percipient.  To  be  sure,  these  physical  objects 
are  centers  of  characteristic  qualities  themselves  universal; 
many  different  objects  possess  the  same  qualities;  therefore 
objects  may  be  classified  according  to  their  kind  in  a  teleo- 
logical  system.  But  this  feature  of  the  sense-world  is  alto 
gether  over-shadowed  by  the  fact  that  its  objects  owe  their 
standing  and  existence  to  the  widely  differing  motor  adjust 
ments  of  different  individuals  and  are  hence  particular  things 
externally  juxtaposed. 

But  thought  is  not  content  with  interpreting  the  succes 
sive  situations  in  which  different  individuals  find  themselves 
with  a  view  to  possible  action;  it  endeavors  to  extract  the 


196  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

essential  significance  of  the  passing  experiences  of  all  in 
dividuals  and  give  to  the  meaning  thus  discovered  and 
defined,  valid  as  it  is  for  all  human  agents,  permanent  ex 
pression  through  the  medium  of  language.  By  means  of  the 
concept,  thought  advances  toward  the  attainment  of  its  aim 
of  formulating  in  an  ideal  system  all  objects  that  can  be 
realized.  The  concept  is  an  identification  of  objects  that 
play  a  similar  part  in  all  human  conduct,  this  identical  func 
tion  being  symbolized  by  a  word.  The  relations  which  con 
stitute  the  meaning  of  such  concepts  are  of  two  kinds,  because 
the  functions  which  objects  discharge  in  voluntary  action 
are  of  two  main  sorts.  Such  objects  are  either  links  or  steps 
in  sequences  of  movement  or  else  they  are  sources  of  satis 
faction.  Conceptual  objects  are  therefore  possessed  either 
of  spatial  attributes,  and  thus  are  subject  to  mechanical 
causation,  or  of  the  properties  of  freedom  and  self-develop 
ment.  The  meaning  of  most  familiar  concepts  is  constituted 
by  both  these  types  of  relation;  they  are  at  once  extended 
objects  having  location,  size,  shape,  etc.,  depending  in  their 
construction  and  employment  upon  definite  kinds  of  motor 
adjustment,  and  also  objects  of  value  having  many  possibil 
ities  of  use  and  promising  a  variety  of  satisfactions.  Terms 
which  thus  symbolize  the  permanent  significance,  mechanical 
or  teleological,  of  the  changing  objects  of  experience  are 
themselves  combined  according  to  their  essential  relations 
into  propositions  and  propositions  are  woven  into  larger 
bodies  of  discourse.  Such  systems  of  discourse,  developed 
by  individual  thought  and  general  discussion,  when  freed 
from  inner  contradiction  and  tested  by  common  human  ex 
perience,  stand  as  the  accepted  truth.  When  a  statement  of 
supposed  fact  conforms  to,  or  is  implied  in,  this  body  of  veri 
fied  knowledge,  it  is  judged  true;  but  when  it  contradicts 
established  propositions,  it  is  judged  false  and  its  object 
unreal.1 

1  In  this  and  the  foregoing  paragraph  quotations  are  made  from  the 
writer's  article,  "The  Object  of  Perception  versus  the  Object  of  Thought," 
Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific  Methods,  Vol.  XIII, 
1916,  p.  437. 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          197 

Conceptual  thought  cannot  be  freely  exercised  until  in 
dustrial  and  political  development  have  proceeded  far  enough 
to  make  possible  an  orderly  social  life  in  which  individuals 
are  free  to  exchange  ideas  and  to  engage  in  constant  and 
systematic  discussion  of  their  experiences.  When  these  con 
ditions  were  fulfilled,  it  is  not  strange  that  human  thought 
should  have  turned  its  attention  away  from  the  outer  world 
of  sense-objects  to  the  inner  realm  of  purpose  and  ideal,  and 
devoted  itself  to  an  investigation  of  the  possibilities  of  satis 
faction  offered  by  the  different  ends  of  human  action.  Ob 
jects  were  then  classified  into  a  system  in  accordance  with 
the  kind  or  degree  of  satisfaction  they  promised  and  thus 
constituted  a  realm  of  ends  or  ideals.  The  formulation  of 
such  a  system  of  values  was  tantamount  to  the  discovery  of 
a  new  world,  different  from  and  in  many  ways  contrasting 
with  the  natural.  This  ideal  or  spiritual  realm  was  found  to 
have  its  own  structure  and  organization:  ends  could  be 
classified  in  accordance  with  their  generality  and  all  sub 
sumed  under  one,  the  summum  genus;  they  could  also  be 
organized  according  to  degree  of  comprehensiveness,  all 
being  finally  included  within  one  absolute  and  all-compre 
hensive  good.1 

If  it  is  possible  to  conceive  of  objects  altogether  in  terms 
of  the  variety  of  satisfactions  which  they  offer,  it  is  also  pos 
sible  to  conceive  of  them  exclusively  in  terms  of  their  me 
chanical  conditions.  This  modern  physical  science  has  done; 
it  has  eliminated  all  secondary  qualities  from  the  actual  world 
and  reduced  its  phenomena  to  terms  of  mass  and  motion. 
Hence  the  two  worlds,  that  of  value  and  that  of  mechanism, 
confront  one  another  in  the  systematic  thought  of  the  pres 
ent:  they  are  not  merely  different,  they  are  opposed;  they 
are  not  merely  antagonistic,  they  seem  out  of  all  conceivable 
relation  to  one  another.  Yet  both  formulations  are  valid 
because,  as  we  have  seen,  the  categories  on  which  both  are 
based,  of  teleology  and  mechanism,  are  grounded  in  the  na 
ture  of  volition,  which  is  fundamental  to  human  experience 

1  Cf.  H.  W.  Wright,  Faith  Justified  by  Progress,  New  York,  1916,  Lecture 
IV,  "The  Supernatural  Life." 


198  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

and  conditions  the  existence  of  thought  itself  as  a  form  of 
voluntary  activity.  Despite  the  apparent  finality  of  this 
dualism,  our  thought  chafes  under  it,  and  it  is  the  special 
task  of  present-day  philosophy  to  find  some  principle  com 
prehensive  enough  to  reconcile  these  two  orders  of  movement 
and  choice,  necessity  and  freedom,  matter  and  spirit. 

The  question  of  transcending  the  dualism  of  mind  and 
matter  now  recurs  in  a  somewhat  different  form:  Does  not 
our  experience  of  voluntary  activity  supply  such  a  synthesis 
as  we  require?  Is  not  the  realization  of  the  end  itself  a  recon 
ciliation  of  free  choice  and  effortful  movement?  More 
specifically,  does  not  the  experience  of  realization  establish 
a  relation  of  adjustment  between  free  choice  and  mechanical 
determination,  and  does  this  relation  not  furnish  us  with  the 
reconciling  category  which  we  seek?  Evidently  this  relation 
is  not  as  obvious  as  those  which  gain  expression  in  mechanism 
and  teleology  or  it  would  have  influenced  human  thought  as 
decisively  as  the  other  two.  But,  however  obscure,  it  is 
worth  investigating,  for  in  it  lies  the  only  apparent  hope  of 
a  solution  for  the  crucial  philosophical  problem. 

An  idea  is  realized,  according  to  the  account  already  given, 
when  the  movements  at  the  command  of  the  agent  are  such 
as  to  revive  and  reinforce  rather  than  to  exclude  its  con 
stituent  qualities.  Now  the  movements  at  the  command  of 
the  agent  are  principally  the  movements  of  his  own  body, 
muscular  co-ordinations  established  by  heredity  or  practice 
and  performed  without  effort  or  attention.  An  idea  realized 
is  an  idea  brought  into  existence,  and  an  existing  object  is 
an  object  that  the  agent  sees  or  hears,  handles  or  manipu 
lates,  describes  to  himself  or  otherwise  reacts  to.  What  dif 
ference  does  it  make  to  an  ideal  quality  thus  to  be  brought 
into  harmony  with  the  motor  adjustment  of  the  human  or 
ganism?  It  means,  in  the  first  place,  that  the  qualities  in 
question  may  be  re-experienced  by  the  agent  whenever  he 
chooses  to  repeat  the  movements  necessary  to  their  revival. 
It  means,  in  the  second  place,  that  the  object  may  also  be 
experienced  by  all  other  individuals  who,  imagining  its  char 
acter  from  the  speech  and  expression  of  the  agent,  watch 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          199 

and  imitate  the  movements  by  which  he  has  realized  it. 
For  an  end  to  be  realized  signifies,  therefore,  that  it  ceases 
to  be  the  momentary  choice  of  an  individual  will  and  becomes 
the  potential  property  of  all  individual  wills,  a  permanent 
source  of  social  satisfaction.  The  human  organism  is  the 
medium  or  instrument  through  which  ends  are  thus  social 
ized.  Influenced  by  convention,  we  often  think  of  human 
bodies  as  strictly  individual  possessions,  expressing  individ 
uality  in  its  most  private  and  exclusive  character.  This  is 
far  from  the  truth;  it  is  his  body  with  its  inherited  mechan 
isms  that  allies  the  individual  with  his  race  or  species.  In 
dividuality  finds  expression  in  those  purposes  and  preferences 
which  are  shaped  and  formulated  by  the  free  imagination 
of  the  individual  and  which  are  original  with  and  distinctive 
of  him.  His  body  is  the  instrument  by  which  he  converts 
these  original  purposes  into  sources  of  social  satisfaction. 
It  appears,  then,  that  the  relation  brought  to  light  in  the 
realization  of  an  end  is  that  of  association,  since  the  objects 
experienced  are  determined  neither  by  the  free  choice  of  an 
individual  will  nor  by  the  constraint  of  objective  reality  but 
by  the  conditions  of  social  life  and  activity. 

The  conclusion  to  which  we  come  is  that  the  association 
of  individual  wills  who  pursue  correlative  ends  under  the 
same  objective  limitations  is  the  comprehensive  relationship 
which  reconciles  mechanism  and  teleology.  The  experience 
of  realizing  an  end  is  an  experience  both  of  movement  and 
of  choice;  with  the  object  once  in  his  possession  the  agent 
makes  the  bodily  adjustments  which  are  necessary  to  rein 
force  those  of  its  qualities  which  he  may  choose  to  expe 
rience.  But  necessity  and  freedom  are  not  simply  combined 
in  an  external  way  in  realization;  they  are  both  transformed 
through  integration  in  a  higher  unity.  The  experience  of 
movement  is  no  longer  the  experience  of  overcoming  re 
sistance,  of  expending  effort;  it  takes  the  form  of  kinaesthetic 
qualities  which  have  meaning  because  they  identify  them 
selves  with  other  actions  of  the  agent  and  his  fellows.  This 
is  true  of  the  movements  of  the  body  and  sensory  apparatus 
by  which  we  maintain  our  positions  and  adjust  ourselves  to 


200  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

one  another  in  the  common  world;  it  is  also  true  of  those  of 
the  speech-mechanism,  which,  as  an  instrument  of  communi 
cation,  has  always  a  social  reference.  It  has  been  generally 
recognized  that  kinaesthetic  qualities  perform  an  important 
office  in  imparting  objectivity  to  the  other  qualities  with 
which  they  are  interwoven;  this  is  because  they  give  these 
latter  qualities,  whose  experience  is  desired,  a  definite  place 
in  the  common  world  of  human  occupations  and  intercourse. 
Nor  is  the  freedom  which  we  exercise  in  the  enjoyment  or 
use  of  the  object  realized  identical  with  the  freedom  we  enjoy 
when  we  imagine  its  various  qualities.  The  ability  to  follow 
the  play  of  imagination  in  projecting  objects  for  possible 
realization  is  freedom  in  the  more  restricted  and  proper 
sense;  its  activity  has,  however,  a  certain  arbitrariness  be 
cause  subject  solely  to  the  individual  will.  But  the  freedom 
which  we  exercise  in  choosing  this  or  that  quality  or  char 
acter  of  the  existing  object  for  our  use  or  enjoyment  is 
limited  by  the  fact  that  all  these  qualities  have  been  brought 
into  definite  relations  with  the  determinate  motor  adjust 
ments  of  a  human  organism.  The  choice  of  the  individual  is 
no  longer  determined  solely  by  his  own  will  and  the  character 
of  his  own  experience;  it  is  determined  by  the  general  will 
of  mankind  and  the  conditions  of  social  life. 

The  social  significance  of  the  experience  of  realization  is 
frequently  obscured  by  the  fact  that  the  experience  in  ques 
tion  is  exemplified  by  the  attainment  of  some  particular 
desire.  Not  that  the  social  implication  is  absent  in  this  case; 
qualities  which,  when  imagined  as  desirable,  express  the  will 
of  a  single  individual  become  in  the  process  of  realization 
associated  with  movements  which  take  place  in  the  world 
of  common  perception  and  which  can  be  imitated  and  em 
ployed  by  others  to  induce  an  experience  of  the  same  char 
acter.  But  this  social  reference  becomes  much  plainer  in 
the  realization  of  a  comprehensive  purpose  whose  attain 
ment  involves  the  employment  of  tools  and  the  control  of 
natural  forces  and  whose  satisfactions  extend  over  a  con 
siderable  period  of  time.  Consider,  as  an  example,  the  pur 
pose  to  grow  a  crop  of  grain  for  the  winter's  food-supply. 


IS  THE  DUALISM  OF  MIND  AND  MATTER  FINAL?          2OI 

The  successive  movements  by  which  the  end  is  realized,  de 
pending  upon  the  use  of  tools  and  following  uniform  se 
quences  of  nature,  become  generalized  community  practices, 
established  arts,  and,  because  of  the  opportunities  they  offer 
for  co-operation,  independent  sources  of  satisfaction.    And 
the  satisfactions  which  these  movements  bring  about  are 
enjoyed  by  several  individuals  in  association  and  imply  an 
orderly  community  life  with  its  many  and  varied  possibilities 
of  intercourse,  companionship,  and  play  around  the  fireside 
hearth  or  on  the  village  common.    The  social  character  of 
our  experience  of  reality  is  fully  revealed,  however,  only  in 
the  achievement  of  the  three  universal  ends  sought  by  voli 
tion  in  its  specialized  capacities  of  thought  and  action  and 
feeling,  viz.,  Truth  and  Power  and  Beauty.     Each  of  these 
ends  is  being  progressively  realized:  the  system  of  verifiable 
ideas  is  being  enlarged  and  co-ordinated;  more  methods  of 
operation  are  being  devised  and  machines  invented;  new 
arrangements  of  form  and  color  and  tone  are  being  effected 
which  stimulate  the  imagination  and  arouse  the  feeling  of 
beauty.     In  each  case,  the  movements  involved  are  them 
selves  instruments  of  association:  language  of  communica 
tion,  industrial  technique  of  co-operation,  aesthetic  contem 
plation  of  fellow-feeling.     And  these  ends  have  all  of  them  in 
their  realization  the  same  social  implication  of  the  establish 
ment  of  a  society  of  free  persons  united  by  mutual  under 
standing,  co-operation,  and  sympathy  in  the  experience  of  a 
common  world  of  intelligible  objects,  manageable  forces,  and 
enjoyable  harmonies  of  sight  and  of  sound. 

If  these  conclusions  are  warranted,  philosophy  has  erred 
when,  influenced  by  the  definitive  opposition  of  mechanism 
and  teleology,  it  has  conceived  reality  either  as  a  kinetic 
system  or  as  a  hierarchy  of  ends,  rather  than  as  a  social  life. 
Our  social  experience  presents  a  reality  more  concrete,  if 
less  definite,  richer  and  more  varied,  if  less  easily  formu 
lated;  surely  there  is  no  more  promising  field  for  philosophical 
investigation  than  that  of  man's  developing  social  life,  his 
progressive  cultural  achievements. 


THE  REVOLT  AGAINST  DUALISM  l 
ALFRED  H.  JONES 

U!T  is  a  commonplace  of  our  philosophical  tradition  that 
Kant  marks  a  turning  point  in  the  history  of  modern  thought. 
The  Kantian  and  post-Kantian  systems  are  forces  with 
which  we  have  to  reckon  at  the  present  day,  .  .  .  while  the 
earlier  theories  of  the  modern  period,  though  not  lacking  in 
suggestion,  are  generally  taken  to  represent  standpoints  and 
methods  which  have  been  definitely  transcended.  .  .  .  Kant 
himself  was  so  impressed  with  the  importance  of  the  new 
principle  which  he  introduced  into  philosophy  that  he  spoke 
of  it  as  a  revolution  comparable  to  that  which  Copernicus 
had  brought  about  in  astronomy.  And,  in  spite  of  occasional 
dissenting  voices,  this  verdict  seems  to  have  been  generally 
accepted,  not  only  by  his  immediate  successors,  but  also  by 
philosophers  of  the  present  day.  .  .  .  Kant's  own  state 
ment  of  the  nature  of  the  change  which  he  had  brought 
about  is  well  known.  Whereas  previous  philosophy  had 
proceeded  on  the  assumption  that  the  mind  is  determined 
in  the  process  of  knowledge  by  an  object  external  to  itself, 
his  philosophy  is  the  proof  that  the  object  must  conform  to 
the  conditions  prescribed  by  the  knowing  mind.  Thus  the 
centre  of  the  philosophical  universe  is  changed  from  the  ob 
ject  to  the  knowing  subject:  we  have  to  recognize  that  the 
understanding  gives  laws  to  nature.  Now,  if  Kant  is  himself 
the  final  authority  regarding  the  meaning  of  his  philosophy, 
and  if  this  statement  is  to  be  taken  literally  as  complete  and 
final,  then  one  would  be  justified  in  feeling  that  his  new 
principle  is  of  questionable  validity.  .  .  .  The  'mind'  in 
the  sense  of  the  older  philosophy,  has  no  advantage  as  a 

1  This  essay,  so  far  as  it  deals  with  the  philosophy  of  Thomas  Reid,  is 
similar  to  the  writer's  article  entitled,  "The  Problem  of  Objectivity," 
Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XXV,  1916,  p.  778. 


THE  REVOLT  AGAINST  DUALISM  203 

principle  of  explanation  over  the  merely  external  object. 
Mere  subjectivism  is  no  advance  on  mere  objectivism:  they 
rest  on  the  same  fundamental  assumptions  and  have  so  much 
in  common  that  their  differences  are  almost  negligible.  .  .  . 
Kant  begins  clearly  enough  with  the  ordinary  dualism,  which 
was  common  to  both  the  earlier  schools  of  modern  philos 
ophy;  and  at  first  he  appears  to  be  bringing  together  in  a 
merely  mechanical  way  elements  derived  from  these  his 
torical  sources.  .  .  .  But,  as  one  can  see  through  the  per 
spective  afforded  by  the  intervening  time,  the  significance 
of  the  Critical  philosophy  is  not  dependent  upon  its  success 
in  carrying  out  this  program,  but  is  due  to  the  fact  that  the 
logic  of  its  procedure  transformed  the  standpoint  from  which 
this  problem  had  been  formulated,  and  thus  revealed  that 
the  problem  itself  was  not  a  genuine  one.  .  .  .  His  real 
method  of  procedure,  .  .  .  i.  ^.,  the  procedure  by  means  of 
which  he  obtained  fruitful  results,  assumes  knowledge  and 
its  organization,  and  proceeds  by  reflective  analysis  to  bring 
to  light  the  assumptions  which  are  involved  in  it  as  con 
structive  principles.  .  .  .  The  critical  method,  then,  does 
not  attempt  to  construct  knowledge  or  to  prove  its  existence, 
but  to  formulate  and  systematize  its  necessary  assumptions." 
Such,  in  the  clear  language  of  Professor  Creighton,1  was 
the  significant  revolution  wrought  by  Kant  in  modern  philo 
sophical  thought.  It  was  not,  however,  until  Hegel  that  the 
revolt  thus  falteringly  initiated  against  dualism  attained  full 
consciousness  of  itself.  It  was  Hegel's  proud  boast  that  he 
'broke  through  to  reality;'  that,  premising  a  ready  and 
authentic  intercourse  with  things,  he  expended  the  labor  of 
his  thought  wholly  on  the  analysis  of  the  real  and  the  prin 
ciples  by  which  we  apprehend  it.  Philosophy,  so  considered, 
is  a  *  criticism  of  categories.'  Shunning  the  ancient  ambition 
to  leap  from  the  possessed  to  a  severed  and  foreign  reality, 
philosophers  of  this  type  limit  the  excursions  of  their  thought 
to  the  world  of  present  proprietorship;  their  universe  is  a 
single-chambered  affair.  In  curious  contrast  stands  the  pro- 

1  "The  Copernican  Revolution  in  Philosophy,"  Philosophical  Review, 
Vol.  XXII,  1913,  pp.  133-136. 


204  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

cedure  of  British  metaphysicians,  committed  by  dualistic 
premises  to  the  insoluble  problem  of  unifying  a  world 
regarded,  in  its  inmost  nature,  as  severed  and  split.  Begin 
ning  with  the  assumption  that  matter  is  an  absolute, 
English  thinkers  early  encountered  the  problem  of  error, 
for  real  things  do  appear  falsely.  To  solve  this  difficulty, 
they  postulated  a  second  absolute,  the  mind,  in  the  dark 
recesses  of  which  vagrant  illusions  might  find  shelter  and 
a  home.  Thus  arose  the  classic  doctrine  of  the  twin 
store-houses,  in  one  or  the  other  of  which  the  entire  con 
tent  of  experience  must  lie.  But  this  radical  separation, 
while  settling  one  problem,  gave  rise  to  another  no  less  urgent 
and  perplexing.  "  Is  the  reality  thus  locked  and  barred  out 
side  of  mind  perceivable,"  it  was  asked,  "and  if  so,  how  is 
this  perception  possible?"  To  this  inquiry  there  was  no 
satisfactory  answer.  Thus  the  content  of  the  external  store 
house  was  gradually  shifted  to  the  mind,  and  the  real  became 
hypothetical,  a  mere  ghost  of  its  former  self.  "The  great 
advantage  of  ...  [the  dualistic]  theory,"  remark  the  Plat 
form  Realists,  "is  that  it  ...  accounts  for  error  and  illu 
sion;  the  disadvantage  of  it  is  that  it  appears  to  account 
for  nothing  else."  1 

The  reasoning  just  sketched  reveals  at  once  the  achieve 
ment  and  failure  of  British  metaphysics.  To  attain  construc 
tive  significance,  this  philosophy  must  reject  mind  and  matter 
as  substances  and  conceive  them  as  reciprocal  functions  of 
a  self-determining  experience.  It  can  hardly  fail  to  strike 
one  as  strange  that  a  program  so  natural  and  promising  as 
this  has,  in  the  entire  history  of  philosophy  in  English,  been 
tried  but  twice,  first  by  Thomas  Reid,  second  by  the  new 
realists.  Of  the  terms  of  traditional  dualism,  Reid  challenged 
and  re-interpreted  only  the  doctrine  of  mind.  Aroused  from 
the  dogmatic  acceptance  of  the  Berkeleian  theory  by  its 
sceptical  issue  in  the  philosophy  of  Hume,  Reid  examined 
the  foundations  of  the  classic  structure,  and  discovered,  not  a 
little  to  his  surprise,  that  it  "leans  with  its  whole  weight 
upon  a  hypothesis,  which  is  ancient  indeed,  and  hath  been 
1  The  New  Realism,  pp.  4f. 


THE  REVOLT  AGAINST  DUALISM  205 

very  generally  received  by  philosophers,  but  of  which  I  could 
find  no  solid  proof.  The  hypothesis  I  mean,  is,  That  nothing 
is  perceived  but  what  is  in  the  mind  which  perceives  it: 
That  we  do  not  really  perceive  things  that  are  external,  but 
only  certain  images  and  pictures  of  them  imprinted  upon 
the  mind.  ...  If  this  be  true,  ...  I  cannot,  from  their 
existence,  infer  the  existence  of  anything  else."  l 

Reid's  polemic  was  directed  not  against  all  conceptions 
of  ideas,  but  solely  against  the  notion  of  them  as  exclusive 
objects  or  termini  of  knowledge,  motes  and  beams  in  the 
eye  of  the  subject.2  Good  dogmatist  that  he  was,  Reid  holds 
it  self-evident  that  knowledge  is  principally  engaged,  not 
with  its  own  ideas,  but  with  objects.  "When  we  see  the 
sun  or  moon,  we  have  no  doubt  that  the  very  objects  which 
we  immediately  see  are  very  far  distant  from  us,  and  from 
one  another." 3  "A  second  reflection  .  .  .  is — that  the 
authors  who  have  treated  of  ideas,  have  generally  taken  their 
existence  for  granted,  as  a  thing  that  could  not  be  called  in 
question;  and  such  arguments  as  they  have  mentioned  in 
cidentally,  in  order  to  prove  it,  seem  too  weak  to  support  the 
conclusion."  Only  two  arguments,  he  finds,  have  been  ad 
vanced  in  defense  of  the  conception.  The  first,  succinctly 
stated  by  Clarke,  sets  forth  that  "The  soul,  without  being 
present  to  the  images  perceived,  could  not  possibly  perceive 
them.  A  living  substance  can  only  there  perceive,  where  it 
is  present."  4  Of  such  reasoning  Reid  makes  short  work, 
showing  that  whatever  cogency  it  possesses  is  due  to  the 
unacknowledged  premise  that  mind  is  quasi-material.  The 

1  The  Works  of  Thomas  Reid,  edited  by  Sir  W.  Hamilton,  Vol.  I,  p.  96. 
"If  by  ideas  are  meant  only  the  acts  or  operations  of  our  minds  in 
perceiving,  remembering,  or  imagining  objects,  I  am,"  he  affirms,  "far 
from  calling  in  question  the  existence  of  those  acts."  Ibid.,  Vol.  I,  p.  298. 
Cf.  James's  statement:  "Whoever  blots  out  the  notion  of  consciousness 
from  his  list  of  first  principles  must  still  provide  in  some  way  for  that 
function's  being  carried  on."  Essays  in  Radical  Empiricism,  p.  4. 

3  All   quotations,   unless   otherwise   specified,   are  from   the   excellent 
summary  which  constitutes  the  fourteenth  chapter  of  the  second  of  the 
Essays  on  the  Intellectual  Powers  of  Man;  Works,  Vol.  I,  pp.  298-306. 

4  Quoted  by  Reid,  ibid.,  p.  30x3. 


206  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

second  arid  weightier  argument  arises  from  the  fact  of  the 
variability  of  perception  and  illusion.  "The  table  .  .  .  ," 
Hume  remarked,  "seems  to  diminish  as  we  remove  farther 
from  it:  but  the  real  table  .  .  .  suffers  no  alteration.  It 
was,  therefore,  nothing  but  its  image  which  was  present  to 
the  mind."  1  To  this,  the  true  ground  of  all  subjectivism, 
Reid  has  no  adequate  or  convincing  reply.  He  merely  affirms, 
partly  on  the  right  track,  that  there  is  no  reason  why  real 
objects,  under  different  conditions  of  perception,  should  not 
array  themselves  in  different  garments;  and  further  reminds 
us  that  the  forms  and  successions  of  appearances  are  as 
predictable  as  those  of  real  things  themselves — a  fact,  he 
believes,  consonant  only  with  the  hypothesis  of  realism.2 
"Thus,"  he  concludes,  "I  have  considered  every  argument 
I  have  found  advanced  to  prove  the  existence  of  ideas  .  .  . 
in  the  mind;  and,  if  no  better  arguments  can  be  found,  I 
cannot  help  thinking  that  the  whole  history  of  philosophy 
has  never  furnished  an  instance  of  an  opinion  so  unanimously 
entertained  by  philosophers  upon  so  slight  grounds." 

Reid's  remaining  criticisms  have  a  common  aim,  to  reduce 
the  theory  of  ideas  to  an  absurdity.  "If  ideas  be  not  a  mere 
fiction,  they  must  be,  of  all  objects  of  human  knowledge,  the 
things  we  have  best  access  to  know  .  .  .  ;  yet  there  is  noth 
ing  about  which  men  differ  so  much."  He  observes  further 
that  "ideas  do  not  make  any  of  the  operations  of  the  mind 
to  be  better  understood,  although  it  was  probably  with  that 
view  that  they  have  been  first  invented.  .  .  .  We  are  at 
a  loss  to  know  how  we  perceive  distant  objects;  how  we  re 
member  things  past;  how  we  imagine  things  that  have  no 
existence.  .  .  .  They  are  all  by  means  of  ideas  reduced  to 
one  operation — to  a  kind  of  feeling,  or  immediate  perception 

1  Quoted  by  Reid,  Works,  Vol.  I,  p.  302. 

2  "Shall  we  say,"  he  inquires,  "that  a  false  supposition,  invented  by 
the  rude  vulgar,  has  been  so  lucky  in  solving  an  infinite  number  of  phe 
nomena  of  nature  ?    This,  surely,  would  be  a  greater  prodigy  than  philoso 
phy  ever  exhibited :  add  to  this,  that,  upon  the  contrary  hypothesis,  .  .  . 
no  account  can  be  given  of  any  of  these  appearances,  nor  any  physical 
cause  assigned  why  a  visible  object  should,  in  any  one  case,  have  one 
apparent  figure  and  magnitude  rather  than  another." 


THE  REVOLT  AGAINST  DUALISM  207 

of  things  present  and  in  contact  with  the  percipient;  and 
feeling  is  an  operation  so  familiar  that  we  think  it  needs  no 
explication,  but  may  serve  to  explain  other  operations.  But 
this  feeling,  or  immediate  perception,  is  as  difficult  to  com 
prehend  as  the  things  which  we  pretend  to  explain  by  it." 
Finally,  it  is  in  consequence  of  this  doctrine  that  subjectiv- 
ists  feel  it  "necessary  to  prove,  by  philosophical  arguments, 
the  existence  of  material  objects.  And  who  does  not  see 
that  philosophy  must  make  a  very  ridiculous  figure  in  the 
eyes  of  sensible  men,  while  it  is  employed  in  mustering  up 
metaphysical  arguments,  to  prove  that  there  is  a  sun  and  a 
moon,  an  earth  and  a  sea?  .  .  .  However  [he  concludes],  as 
these  paradoxes  have,  with  great  acuteness  and  ingenuity, 
been  deduced  by  just  reasoning  from  the  theory  of  ideas, 
they  must  at  last  bring  this  advantage,  that  positions  .  .  . 
so  contrary  to  the  decisions  of  all  our  intellectual  powers, 
will  open  men's  eyes,  and  break  the  force  of  the  prejudice 
which  hath  held  them  entangled  in  that  theory." 

There  is  in  these  statements  much  that  is  ill-considered 
and  utterly  dogmatic;  but  we  should  not,  on  that  account, 
fail  to  observe  that  they  set  forth,  for  the  first  time,  in  opposi 
tion  to  British  dualism,  the  outlines  of  a  doctrine  of  imme 
diate  perception  of  reality.  It  is  the  more  to  be  regretted, 
therefore,  that  Reid  failed  to  sustain  and  develop  this  sugges 
tive  insight.  That  mind  was  a  substance  or  agent,  and  that 
sensation  and  feeling  formed  the  material  of  such  substances, 
he  never  questioned.  "  By  the  mind  of  a  man,"  he  writes,  "  we 
understand  that  in  him  which  thinks,  remembers,  reasons, 
wills."  Sensation,  he  continues,  "hath  no  object  distinct 
from  the  act  itself";  "the  feeling  and  the  thing  felt  are  one 
and  the  same."  1  Perception,  memory,  and  imagination, 
according  to  Reid,  reveal  to  us  objects  independent  of  our 
selves;  but  sensation  and  feeling  have  no  content  save  their 
own  character  and  state.  It  was  at  these  points,  accordingly, 
that  the  germs  of  subjectivism  entered  Reid's  system,  and, 
after  the  manner  of  their  kind,  multiplied  and  spread,  until 
they  infected  most  of  it.  By  degrees,  the  secondary  and 
1  Works,  Vol.  I,  pp.  220,  229,  230,  respectively. 


208  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

then  the  primary  qualities  contracted  the  ailment,  and  be 
came,  in  effect,  mere  states  of  mind.  The  result  is  an  incon 
sequential  doctrine  of  perception  for  which  Reid,  owing  to 
the  misdirected  efforts  of  his  expositors,  is  mainly  known: 
the  theory  that  sensations  are  but  signs  or  signals  which 
initiate  in  the  mind  a  ' conception'  of  objects  and  an  irre 
sistible  belief  in  their  existence.  According  to  this  inter 
pretation,  what  assures  us  of  reality  is  no  direct  seizure  of  it, 
but  a  common-sense  conviction  of  its  existence,  supposed  for 
theoretical  as  for  practical  purposes  to  be  authoritative  and 
ultimate. 

This  summary  suffices  to  exhibit  the  grave  manner  in 
which  Reid's  house  is  divided  against  itself.  Affirming,  in 
opposition  to  Berkeley  and  Hume,  a  suggestive  doctrine  of 
immediate  perception,  this  author,  determined  by  subjective 
premises,  insensibly  drifted  back,  in  the  constructive  move 
ment  of  his  thought,  into  the  very  theory  of  ideas  which  he 
proposed  to  controvert.  Nor  was  the  breach  thus  left  open 
satisfactorily  closed  by  any  succeeding  philosopher  of  the 
Scottish  School.  Influenced  by  Hamilton,  a  man  of  prodi 
gious  learning  but  of  little  genius,  these  philosophers  re 
jected  Reid's  suggestion  of  monistic  realism,  following  instead 
the  familiar  theory  of  representative  perception.  Not  un 
til  the  last  decade,  and  then  outside  of  Scotland,  and  with 
out  historical  relation  to  Reid,  has  there  been  a  fresh  attempt 
to  formulate  the  sole  original  feature  of  Scotch  meta 
physics.  This  formulation  has  been  undertaken  by  the  new 
realists. 

The  new  realism,  particularly  that  of  Professor  Perry, 
in  its  relation  to  dualism,  consists  in  developing  the  con 
sequences  of  a  single  postulate,  viz.,  that  the  content  of 
experience  is  'neutral'  in  character.  Is  the  l psychical'  an 
aspect  or  relation  of  that  which  is  likewise  'physical,'  or  are 
they  separate  and  unique  existences?  l  Modern  realism 
returns  to  the  first  part  of  this  question  an  affirmative,  to 

1  Cf.  "Topic  for  Discussion  at  the  1916  Meeting  of  the  American  Philo 
sophical  Association,"  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific 
Methods,  Vol.  XIII,  1916,  pp.  573!. 


THE  REVOLT  AGAINST  DUALISM  209 

the  second  part,  a  negative  reply.  "In  so  far  as  I  divide 
them  into  elements,"  writes  Professor  Perry,  "the  contents 
of  my  mind  exhibit  no  generic  character.  ...  It  is  only 
with  respect  to  their  grouping  and  interrelations  that  the 
elements  of  mental  content  exhibit  any  peculiarity."  "The 
same  elements,"  viz.,  sensible  qualities  and  logical  cate 
gories,  "compose  both  mind  and  body,"  so  that,  "instead  of 
conceiving  reality  as  divided  absolutely  between  two  im 
penetrable  spheres,  we  may  conceive  it  as  a  field  of  inter 
penetrating  relationships,  among  which  those  described  by 
physics  and  psychology  are  the  most  familiar  and  typical, 
and  those  described  by  logic  the  most  simple  and  universal." 
Mars,  in  brief,  is  ' mental '  in  "relation  to  my  perceiving  ac 
tivity,  .  .  .  my  memories,  plans,  feelings,  etc.";  'physical' 
"by  virtue  of  its  volume,  and  its  distance  from  the  sun."  l 
"There  must  be,"  exclaims  a  vigorous  critic  of  this  doc 
trine,2  "more  than  an  external  correspondence  between  the 
'idea'  and  the  object.  The  idea  ...  is  the  interpretation 
of  the  object,  the  revelation  of  its  nature.  This  revelation 
finds  illustration  in  the  fact  that  cognitive  experience  may 
always  be  read  both  in  internal  and  external  terms;  as  the 
ideas  and  judgments  of  a  mind,  and  as  the  determinations 
of  real  things.  In  its  concreteness,  it  is  both."  In  every 
monistic  metaphysics  the  doctrine  of  neutral  elements,  or 
its  equivalent,  is  manifest.3 

1  Present  Philosophical  Tendencies,  pp.  277,  311,  312. 

2  Professor  Creighton,  "The  Determination  of  the  Real,"  Philosophical 
Review,  Vol.  XXI,  1912,  p.  314. 

s  Cf.  Professor  Dewey,  "The  Concept  of  the  Neutral  in  Recent  Epis- 
temology,"  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific  Methods, 
Vol.  XIV,  1917,  p.  161.  Professor  Dewey  points  out  that  the  neutral 
may  be  conceived  in  either  of  two  senses  and  recommends  greater  ex- 
plicitness  in  the  use  of  the  term.  "In  one  sense  to  call  anything  neutral 
means  neutral  in  a  specified  respect  or  reference;  that  is,  with  respect  to  the 
application  of  a  particular  set  of  alternatives.  .  .  .  To  say,  for  example, 
that  certain  things  are  neutral  with  respect  to  the  distinction  of  mental 
and  material  would  be  to  say  that  there  are  things  such  that  intelligent 
discussion  of  them  is  not  forwarded  by  applying  to  them,  without  further 
specification,  the  distinctions  marked  out  by  the  terms  'mental — material.' 
What  is  asserted  is  the  irrelevancy  of  a  certain  type  of  distinction.  .  .  . 


210  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

This  central  conception  has  two  evident  applications. 
First,  it  denies  that  mind  and  ideas  are  substantial  entities. 
Consciousness,  it  affirms,  is  an  attribute  or  relation.  Though 
general  and  ambiguous  in  form,  this  dictum  has  in  practice  a 
definite  and  specific  meaning,  viz.,  that  the  content  of  per 
ception  is  a  datum  that  is,  or  may  be,  objective.  This  is  the 
essence  of  monistic  metaphysics.  Introduce  any  cleft  be 
tween  the  material  known  and  that  which  exists, — let  the 
first  be  of  one  order  and  the  second  of  another, — and  the 
face  of  things  is  veiled  from  us  forever.  All  that  an  hypothe 
sis  of  immediate  perception  need  maintain,  all  that  its  for 
mulae  can  possibly  mean,  is  that  the  content  of  knowledge 
belongs  exclusively  neither  to  the  world  of  ideas  nor  to  that 
of  things.  It  is  precisely  to  make  intelligible  such  dual  citi 
zenship  as  this  that  members  of  the  current  school  define 
mind  as  a  function  or  relation.  The  content  of  consciousness, 
considered  as  substance,  must  partake  exclusively  of  the  na 
ture  of  that  substance,  but  the  datum  of  thought,  regarded 
as  relation,  is  not  necessarily  of  this  single,  one-dimensional 
character.  On  the  relational  view,  that  which  in  virtue  of  one 
connection  is  known  may  in  virtue  of  another  exist.  By  the 
simple  device  of  substituting  a  dualism  of  relations  for  a 
dualism  of  worlds  the  new  realist  exhibits  reality  as  knowable. 

The  second  application  of  the  doctrine  concerns  the  notion 
of  reality.  It  will  be  recalled  that  Reid,  apart  from  the 
negation  of  ideas,  was  a  naive,  a  common-sense  realist.  Like 
all  metaphysicians  influenced  solely  by  English  tradition,  he 
accepted  without  question,  as  warranted  by  the  senses,  the 
notion  that  matter  is  primordial  and  unique,  one  of  two 
charter  members  in  the  corporation  of  the  universe.  In  op 
position  to  this  time-honored  belief,  the  members  of  the  new 
school  assume  that,  save  for  a  difference  of  relation,  reality 
and  true  knowledge  are  identical.  They  maintain  with 

In  contrast  with  this  conceivable  meaning  of  the  term  neutral,  which 
might  be  called  the  logical,  stands  another  which  might  be  called  the 
metaphysical  or  ontological,  namely,  that  there  is  a  certain  sort  of  stuff 
which  is,  intrinsically,  neutral."  The  word  neutral  is  here  used  only  in 
the  first  of  these  senses.  No  value,  I  believe,  attaches  to  the  second  usage. 


THE  REVOLT  AGAINST  DUALISM  211 

Berkeley  that  existence  is  akin  to  thought;  with  Reid  that  it  is 
no  mere  state  of  mind.  Berkeleianism  robbed  of  substantial 
mind  and  idea,  naive  realism  stripped  of  matter  as  absolute, 
dualism  shorn  of  both  additions,  yield  alike  the  simple  con 
struction  of  the  new  realism.  To  view  the  manifold  content 
of  experience  as  unsupported  and  unexplained  by  any  tran 
scendent  factor  is  to  arrive  at  the  central  insight  of  the 
current  doctrine. 

It  is  accordingly  only  in  a  specific  and  defined  sense  that 
reality  is  independent  of,  or  external  to,  the  process  by 
which  it  is  perceived.  It  stands  outside  the  perceiving  re 
lation  in  the  circumstance  that  it  is  regarded  as  real  solely 
in  virtue  of  its  relation  to  other  objects,  not  because  of  its 
connection  with  the  subject.  Thus  the  moon  is  external  to 
my  perception  in  that  its  position  and  motion  are  deter 
mined,  not  in  terms  of  my  apprehension,  but  in  relation  to 
the  motion  of  other  spheres.  Objects,  in  brief,  are  inde 
pendent  of  perception,  but  not  of  conception.  To  affirm  the 
independence  and  externality  of  the  real  without  qualifica 
tion  is  to  identify  the  new  doctrine  with  dogmatic  or  naive 
realism. 

Reality,  in  such  a  view,  is  deprived  of  all  stiffness;  it  is  a 
conceptual  construction,  a  product  of  the  activity  of  thought. 
It  is  true  that  objects  are  relatively  self-enclosed  and  stable, 
but  this  character,  so  far  from  being  original  and  inherent, 
is  secondary  and  derived.  Cut  out  of  a  larger  and  plastic 
context  by  thought,  objects  are  endowed  with  the  marks  of 
the  real  by  the  very  process  to  which  they  are  commonly 
considered  antithetical.  Such  a  flexible  notion  of  matter 
entails  no  insoluble  problem  of  appearance.  For  reality  and 
appearance,  on  this  view,  differ  not  as  one  order  from  another, 
but  as  a  section  of  cloth  differs  from  a  larger  piece  from  which 
it  has  been  excised.  The  part  cut  out,  because  more  useful, 
is  called  real;  the  remainder,  mere  appearance.  The  true  dif 
ference  between  the  two  sections  is  one  of  value  to  the  cutter. 
Reality  and  appearance  are  in  truth  but  concepts  of  praise 
and  blame;  we  employ  the  first  or  the  second  according  as 
we  desire  to  extol  or  disparage.  The  hoary  problem  of 


212  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

locating  vagrant  illusions  thus  loses  its  meaning.  The  wheel 
has  come  full  circle;  the  fact  of  appearance,  though  ad 
mitted,  no  longer  threatens  or  disturbs. 

The  essential  character  of  the  new  realism  should  now  be 
evident.  So  far  from  being  a  party,  as  is  supposed,  to  the 
ancient  dispute  between  subjectivism  and  naive  realism,  the 
new  doctrine  is  rather  critic  as  much  of  the  second  as  of  the 
first  of  these  theories,  whose  premises  are  the  same.  Its 
salient  feature  is  the  negation  of  the  conception  of  substance. 
Some  exponents  of  the  doctrine,  imperfectly  grasping  its 
logic,  have,  it  is  true,  denied  spiritual  substance  while  affirm 
ing  the  cognate  conception  of  matter.  But  so  evident  is  it 
that  the  two  absolutes  stand  or  fall  together,  that  this  error 
could  hardly  have  been  committed,  save  that  the  new  inter 
pretation  was  elaborated  in  opposition  to  subjectivism,  and 
so  temporarily  made  an  alliance  with  dogmatic  realism. 
Had  the  latter  been  orthodox  and  regnant,  it  is  probable 
that  the  nascent  hypothesis,  developing  with  a  new  emphasis, 
would  have  been  called  the  'new  idealism.'  Certain  it  is 
that  the  designation  ' realism'  here  loses  its  historic  signifi 
cance.  In  the  circumstance  that  subjectivism  is  to  some 
degree  critical,  the  current  doctrine  stands,  on  the  whole, 
in  closer  relation  to  it  than  to  common-sense  realism.  It 
might  perhaps  most  fittingly  be  entitled  the  'new  empiri 
cism.' 

What  is  the  significance  of  the  new  realism?  It  is  signifi 
cant,  I  believe,  solely  as  a  revolt  against  the  premises  of 
dualism.  Like  Reid's  reply  to  Hume,  it  is  chiefly  a  critical, 
not  a  constructive,  undertaking.  By  it,  philosophers  indoc 
trinated  with  the  postulates  of  British  thought  may  be  con 
ducted  to  the  standpoint  of  monistic  metaphysics,  but  in 
the  elaboration  of  the  latter  system  they  will  be  advanced 
scarcely  a  step.  It  is  for  this  reason,  no  doubt,  that  philos 
ophers  like  Professor  Creighton,  though  standing  in  no  es 
sential  opposition  to  the  new  doctrine,  view  it  neverthe 
less  with  indifference.  For  while  it  is  the  merit  of  the 
new  realism  to  have  rejected  as  pseudo-problems  the  con 
struction  of  knowledge  and  the  demonstration  of  its  va- 


THE  REVOLT  AGAINST  DUALISM  213 

lidity,  it  is  its  defect  not  to  have  sharpened  its  con 
cepts  with  reference  to  any  other  difficulties.  Indeed,  the 
sole  aim  of  the  doctrine  is  just  to  construct,  on  the  as 
sumption  of  immediate  perception  of  reality,  a  system 
of  principles  opposed  point  for  point  to  the  structure  of 
dualism,  and  so  to  refute  the  latter.  But  as  not  infrequently 
occurs,  this  aim  entailed  a  degree  of  bondage  to  the  concep 
tion  controverted.  To  refute  the  notion  that  mind  and 
matter  are  substances,  the  new  realism  committed  itself 
thoughtlessly  to  an  image  no  less  concrete  and  picturable, 
that  of  discrete  neutral  states.  Though  effective  against  the 
inveterate  dogmas  of  an  ancient  tradition,  this  static  and 
atomistic  notion  is  far  too  crude  a  tool  to  serve  in  the  erec 
tion  of  a  complex  monistic  metaphysics.  Justly  to  view  the 
world  from  this  standpoint,  the  philosopher  must  attain  to 
the  subtle,  unpictureable  conception  of  experience  as  self- 
sustaining  and  self-determining,  a  process  that  reveals  re 
ciprocally  the  nature  of  subject  and  object.  The  central 
doctrine  of  the  new  realism  is  thus  a  ladder  by  which  to 
mount  from  the  plains  of  dualism  to  the  heights  of  a  strictly 
empirical  philosophy;  once  this  elevation  is  attained,  it  be 
comes  thereafter  an  intolerable  burden. 


SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM 
EDMUND  H.  HOLLANDS 

SOME  fifteen  years  have  passed  since  the  critics  of  prag 
matism  first  objected  that  it  had  taken  no  account  of  the 
oretical  truth  as  distinct  from  'practical';  that  the  thought- 
situations  which  it  discussed  were  always  cases  of  'finding 
one's  way  out  of  the  woods,'  'discovering  the  remedy  for  my 
dyspepsia,'  and  so  on;  and  never  cases  of  'finding  the  alge 
braic  equation  to  a  geometrical  locus,'  'ascertaining  the 
relation  of  the  hypothetical  judgment  to  the  disjunctive,'  or 
'  determining  the  true  cause  of  the  ostracism  of  Themis tocles.' 
The  criticism  seemed  to  hit  a  tender  spot;  at  all  events, 
the  supposed  restriction  of  pragmatic  theory  was  at  once 
disclaimed,  and  rather  indignantly.  It  was  explained  that 
the  'practical'  had  been  meant  to  include  all  interests,  and 
of  course  that  of  theoretical  cognition  among  the  rest.  "It 
is  ...  simply  idiotic,"  said  Professor  James,  for  example, 
"to  repeat  that  pragmatism  takes  no  account  of  purely 
theoretic  interests.  All  it  insists  on  is  that  verity  in  act 
means  verifications,  and  that  these  are  always  particulars."  1 
Such  verifications  for  James  meant  attaining,  getting  to,  a 
sought  percept,  or  a  sought  concept;  for  concepts  belonged 
to  the  manifold  reality,  he  held,  quite  as  much  as  percepts, 
though  in  a  different  order. 

James  did  not  leave  a  finished  system  of  metaphysics 
behind  him;  it  is  left  doubtful,  for  example,  how  far  he  would 
have  required  or  accepted  panpsychism  in  completing  his 
account  of  the  real.  Things-percepts-ideas  and  ideas- 
concepts,  the  physical  order  and  the  psychical  order,  are 
classes  which  cut  across  each  other  in  his  conception  of 
them;  but  they  get  into  working  connection,  so  to  speak, 
in  the  activities  of  living  bodies,  or  at  least  in  those  of  some 

1  The  Meaning  of  Truth,  pp.  21  if. 


SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM  215 

of  them, — 'psycho-physical  organisms.'  This  is  the  position 
in  which  James's  theory  of  reality  and  truth  agrees  with 
that  of  Professor  Dewey  and  the  instrumentalists;  but  while 
he  did  not  develop  it,  and  continued  to  use  the  terminology 
of  introspective  analysis  and  empiricism,  they  have  based 
their  whole  philosophy  on  an  explicit  use  of  organism  and 
environment,  stimulus  and  response,  in  short,  the  categories 
of  biology. 

The  most  important  example  of  this  difference  in  emphasis 
and  method,  it  seems  to  me,  is  to  be  found  in  the  contrast 
between  James's  attempt  at  solving  the  classical  problem 
of  the  'meaning  of  an  idea,'  and  the  answer  given  by  the 
instrumentalists.  Using  the  traditional  terminology,  we  say 
that  the  true  idea  must  agree  with  its  object.  Of  course, 
James  remarked,  we  must  not  take  'agreement'  too  liter 
ally;  any  kind  of  resemblance,  or  getting  at,  or  substitut- 
ability,  that  meets  the  needs  of  the  particular  case,  will  be 
'agreement.'  But  the  object  with  which  the  idea  agrees 
must  be  the  object  which  the  idea  'means';  accidental  agree 
ment,  of  course,  is  not  enough;  agreement  must  be  intended. 
The  question  at  once  occurs,  since  the  whole  connection  re 
ferred  to  is  described  as  a  process  in  time,  how  we  know  in 
advance  what  the  idea  means,  unless  it  transcends  itself,  as 
the  'idealist'  logicians  sometimes  say;  and  James  answered 
that  we  did  not,  that  we  find  out  what  an  idea  really  means 
by  seeing  to  what  it  leads.  In  other  words,  its  meaning 
really  is  its  agreement!  Meaning  is  simply  a  process  of 
leading  begun,  and  agreement  the  same  process  terminated. 
On  this  view,  truth  is  very  literally  something  which  happens 
to  an  idea.  The  circle  in  the  original  definition,  taken  in  this 
way,  seems  evident;  we  ought  not  to  say,  the  true  idea  agrees 
with  its  object,  but,  the  true  idea  agrees  with  some  object. 
But  what  becomes  then  of  the  caution  that  it  must  agree 
with  an  object  which  it  means;  that  "if  it  resemble  without 
operating  on,  it  is  a  dream;  if  it  operate  without  resembling, 
it  is  an  error?"  l 

James  did  not  allow  himself  to  be  troubled  by  the  paradox ; 
1  The  Meaning  of  Truth,  p.  28. 


2l6  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

and  this  was  undoubtedly,  I  should  say,  because  he  felt  that 
the  whole  interest  of  the  question,  as  he  viewed  it,  lay  in  the 
'operation  ',  of  which  the  6 resemblance '  was  only  the  result; 
' meaning'  really  made  ' agreement',  brought  it  into  being. 
In  fact,  agreement  is  the  means,  and  successful  operation 
(operation  with  resembling)  the  end.  The  operation  of  a 
true  idea  (whatever  that  may  be,  and  it  must  be  admitted 
that  the  term  was  a  vague  one  when  extended  to  cover  the 
oretical  knowing)  is  a  process,  then,  which  produces  its  own 
means.  But  this  is  exactly  one  thing  which  we  say  of  life; 
it  is  a  process  which  produces  its  own  means. 

This  is  the  dialectic  by  which  the  pragmatism  of  James 
passes  over  into  the  instrumentalism  of  Dewey.  The  in 
strumentalists  attacked  the  same  problem  by  making  knowl 
edge  from  the  first  and  throughout  an  incident  in  organic 
behavior  of  a  certain  type.  Intelligence  is  regarded  as  a 
series  of  fulgurations,  so  to  speak,  elicited  by  special  diffi 
culties  in  the  adaptation  of  a  living  individual  to  its  environ 
ment,  which  require  a  new  kind  of  response.  ' Agreement' 
from  this  point  of  view  is  successful  functioning  in  such  a 
response,  the  fact  that  the  'idea'  has  been  a  means  in  the 
prosperous  preservation  and  redirection  of  the  organic  ac 
tivities.  Meaning  is  always  a  prospective  matter,  a  leading, 
which  gets  made  and  established,  originally  at  least,  in  the 
active  process  of  choice  and  discovery  when  the  originally 
presented  responses  to  the  given  situation  are  incompatible 
courses  of  action.  How  the  idea  can  mean  in  advance  what 
it  agrees  with  is  thus  an  idle  question.  "The  process  of 
organization  is  as  much  a  process  of  securing  a  stimulus" 
(i.  e.,  meaning)  "as  it  is  a  process  of  securing  response" 
(i.  e.y  agreement).1  The  paradox  is  thus  avoided,  and  mean 
ing  is  accounted  for  without  appeal  to  any  factor  transcend 
ing  the  momentary  situation,  which  in  the  end,  as  it  extends 
beyond  the  focus  of  adjustment,  is  just  the  physical  world. 
How,  at  such  points,  it  proves  capable  of  modification  into 
meanings,  how  existents  can  become  subsistents,  how  the 

1  B.  H.  Bode,  "The  Psychological  Doctrine  of  Focus  and  Margin," 
Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XXIII,  1914,  p.  403. 


SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM  217 

outside  has  an  inside, — this  is  a  mystery;  but  no  more  so 
than  any  other  complexity  appearing  in  the  course  of  things 
over  and  above  its  more  elemental  factors.  "That  suggestion 
occurs  is  doubtless  a  mystery;  but  so  is  it  a  mystery  that 
hydrogen  and  oxygen  make  water.  It  is  one  of  the  hard, 
brute  facts  that  we  have  to  take  account  of."  Use  a  sug 
gested  thing,  "develop  it  in  connection  with  other  meanings 
and  employ  it  as  a  guide  of  investigation,"  and  "you  have 
a  full-fledged  meaning."  1 

The  metaphysics  implied  in  this  logic,  so  much  more  con 
sistently  worked  out  than  that  of  James,  is  evidently  natural 
ism.  What  produces  and  supports  all  values,  including 
truth,  is  the  physical  world,  nature  with  living  men  as  in 
cluded  in  it.  All  verification  is,  in  the  last  resort,  physical. 
"Overt  action  is  demanded  if  the  worth  or  validity  of  the 
reflective  considerations  is  to  be  determined.  Otherwise,  we 
have,  at  most,  only  a  hypothesis  that  the  conditions  of  diffi 
culty  are  such  and  such,  and  that  the  way  to  get  at  them 
so  as  to  get  over  or  through  them  is  so  and  so.  This  way 
must  be  tried  in  action;  it  must  be  applied,  physically,  in 
the  situation.  .  .  .  That  all  knowledge,  as  issuing  from  re 
flection,  is  experimental  (in  the  literal  physical  sense  of  ex 
perimental)  is  then  a  constituent  proposition  of  this  doc 
trine."  I  continue  to  quote,  because  these  statements  of 
Professor  Dewey  are  the  clearest  and  most  definite  in  regard 
to  this  side  of  instrumentalism  that  I  know.  "  The  reason 
it  [thinking]  is  not  an  armchair  thing  is  that  it  is  not  an  event 
going  on  exclusively  within  the  cortex  or  the  cortex  and  the  vocal 
organs.  .  .  .  Hands  and  feet,  apparatus  and  appliances  of 
all  kinds  are  as  much  a  part  of  it  as  changes  in  the  brain.  .  .  . 
Thinking  is  mental,  not  because  of  a  peculiar  stuff  which 
enters  into  it  or  of  peculiar  non-natural  activities  which  con 
stitute  it,  but  because  of  what  physical  acts  and  apparatus 
do;  the  distinctive  purposes  for  which  they  are  employed  and 
the  distinctive  results  which  they  accomplish."  And  "mere 
meaning"  is  "supernatural  or  transcendental  nonsense. 
'Terms'  signify  that  certain  absent  existences  are  indicated 
1  John  Dewey,  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  pp.  49,  50. 


2l8  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

by  certain  given  existences,  in  the  sense  that  they  are  ab 
stracted  and  fixed  for  intellectual  use  by  some  physically  con 
venient  means,  such  as  a  sound  or  a  muscular  contraction  of  the 
vocal  organs"  * 

It  is  evident  that  imageless  thought  would  be  indeed  the 
great  scandal  of  instrumentalism,  worse  than  the  incom 
mensurability  of  the  square's  diagonal  was  for  the  Pythag 
oreans.  But  this  is  perhaps  too  controversial  a  matter  to 
insist  on  now,  though  it  seems  to  me  of  considerable  im 
portance  in  this  connection.  Imageless  thought  would  mean 
a  gap  in  that  physical  series  which  instrumentalism  requires 
to  be  absolutely  continuous,  since  it  identifies  terms  entirely 
with  things.  If  for  the  moment  we  pass  over  this,  and  some 
other  questions  which  might  be  raised  about  the  meaning  of 
what  is  past,  and  so  on,  we  must  admit,  I  think,  that  the 
instrumentalists'  account  of  the  production  of  meanings  in 
practical  situations  of  physical  adjustment  really  does  clear 
many  things  up.  In  fact,  its  straightforward  naturalism  and 
realism,  so  far  taken,  are  genuine  elements  of  appeal  and 
strength  in  their  position. 

But  while  the  instrumentalists  succeed  better  with  the 
question  of  meaning  than  did  James,  it  is  doubtful  whether 
they  can  as  readily  find  room  for  theoretical  knowing  within 
their  account  as  James  could  in  his  less  strait  and  consistent 
theory.  In  one  matter,  to  be  sure,  I  believe  that  Professor 
Dewey's  account  is  to  be  preferred  here  also.  James  usually 
regarded  concepts  as  having  two  kinds  of  value.  Their 
primary  and  direct  use,  of  course,  was  to  take  the  place  of 
the  many  percepts  which  temporal  and  spatial  limitations 
prevented  our  attaining  and  having  directly;  but  then,  in 
the  second  place,  concepts  have  certain  values  of  their  own 
for  our  appreciation,  especially  as  they  fall  into  the  systems 
of  logic  and  mathematics.  The  enriching  overtones  and 
wider  significances  which  such  general  meanings  add  to  ex 
perience,  and  the  thorough  change  in  the  perceptual  which 
is  thus  accomplished,  James  did  not  emphasize.  He  had 

^ohn  Dewey,  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  pp.  I3f.,  and  51,  note. 
Italics  mine. 


SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM  219 

something  of  the  impressionist  about  him,  and  his  ideas  and 
impressions  rather  co-existed  than  fused.  Professor  Dewey 
adequately  recognizes  this  enriching  character  of  the  con 
cept:  "While  reflective  knowing  is  instrumental  to  gaining 
control  in  a  troubled  situation,  ...  it  is  also  instrumental 
to  the  enrichment  of  the  immediate  significance  of  subse 
quent  experiences.  And  it  may  well  be  that  this  by-product, 
this  gift  of  the  gods,  is  incomparably  more  valuable  for  living 
a  life  than  is  the  primary  and  intended  result  of  control, 
essential  as  is  that  control  to  having  a  life  to  live.  .  .  . 
There  exists  no  disjunction  between  aesthetic  qualities  which 
are  final  yet  idle,  and  acts  which  are  practical  or  instru 
mental."  l  This  states  the  matter  well;  but  ought  not  such 
a  recognition  of  the  work  of  mind,  and  of  the  smooth  con 
tinuity  of  the  notional  with  the  total  texture  of  experience, 
to  have  some  modifying  effect  upon  the  naturalistic  basis  of 
this  theory? 

These  functions  of  concepts  are,  however,  only  a  small 
part  of  the  problem  of  theoretical  truth.  The  real  question, 
of  course,  is  whether  there  are  not  thought-situations  never 
adequately  to  be  stated  in  naturalistic  terms.  That  the  situa 
tions  with  which  the  theorist  deals  have,  taken  in  their  en 
tirety,  physical  factors  and  effects,  may  be  in  one  sense  true; 
but  can  they  be  adequately  defined  in  terms  of  these,  or  are 
these  relevant  to  his  specific  interests  in  them?  Once  on  a 
time,  the  scientific  account  of  comets  destroyed  some  false 
beliefs  concerning  their  ominous  significance  for  human 
affairs,  and  thereby  changed  men's  actions.  That  result  is 
over  and  done.  Should  the  scientist  now  withdraw  his 
interest  in  comets  as  no  longer  vital,  or  is  he  justified  in  con 
tinuing  to  study  them?  And  if  so,  why?  How  can  the  study 
in  any  way  help  us  to  a  desired  control  which  is  other  than 
intellectual?  I  can  think  of  but  two  replies  to  such  questions 
as  these,  from  the  point  of  view  of  a  naturalistic  instru- 
mentalism:  either  it  might  be  said  that  such  study  and  in 
terest  is  a  prophylactic  against  the  superstition  which  might 
return  if  it  lapsed,  or  a  faith  might  be  asserted  that  no  knowl- 
1  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  pp.  lyf. 


220  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

edge  whatever  will  be  without  practical  effects  sometime, 
somewhere.    Neither  answer  seems  very  satisfactory. 

Professor  Dewey,  of  course,  recognizes  the  scientific  in 
terest;  but  it  is  described  as  a  professional  or  specialist 
interest.  "In  the  actual  stress  of  any  needed  determination 
it  is  of  the  greatest  importance  to  have  a  large  stock  of 
possible  meanings  to  draw  on,  and  to  have  them  ordered  in 
such  a  way  that  we  can  develop  each  promptly  and  ac 
curately,  and  move  quickly  from  one  to  another.  It  is  not 
to  be  wondered  at  then  that  we  not  only  conserve  such  sug 
gestions  as  have  been  previously  converted  into  meanings, 
but  also  that  we  (or  some  men  at  least)  turn  profes 
sional  inquirers  and  thinkers;  that  meanings  are  elaborated 
and  ordered  in  related  systems  quite  apart  from  any  im 
mediately  urgent  situation."  "As  a  specialised  class  of 
scientific  inquirers  develops,  terms  that  were  originally  by 
products  of  reflection  become  primary  objects  for  the  intel 
lectual  class.  The  troubles  which  occasion  reflection  are 
then  intellectual  troubles,  discrepancies  within  some  current 
scheme  of  propositions  and  terms.  .  .  .  The  resulting  ob 
jects — the  terms  and  propositions — are  for  all,  except  those 
who  produce  them,  instruments,  not  terminal  objects."  1 
How  such  discrepancies  are  physically  present,  as  the  general 
theory  seems  to  require,  is  not  stated.  Presumably  they 
must  be  incompatible  contractions  of  the  vocal  organs  or 
other  like  activities  of  gesture  or  speech,  such  as  terms  are 
defined  as  being.  It  has  been  said  that  the  imagery  of  Platon- 
ists  is  probably  of  the  visual  type,  and  the  same  remark,  I 
believe,  has  been  made  concerning  the  British  Empiricists. 
One  wonders  whether  a  psychological  census  of  the  instru 
mentalists  would  not  put  most  of  them, — or  all, — in  the 
'motilist'  class.  However  this  may  be,  such  statements  as 
those  just  quoted  concerning  theoretical  reflection  seem  to 
take  two  things  for  granted :  first,  that  naive  experience 
raises  no  problems  save  those  of  action;  and  second,  that 
the  theoretical  interest  makes  no  appeal  to  any  but  the 
specialistic  few. 

1  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  pp.  49,  $9f. 


SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM  221 

But  is  it  not  true,  in  the  first  place,  that  it  is  common  sense 
which  produces  most  of  the  problems  for  which  Professor 
Dewey  sometimes  reproaches  philosophy,  since  he  regards 
them  as  unreal  and  futile?  How  a  mind  can  know  things, 
how  the  soul  and  body  are  related  to  each  other, — these  and 
other  problems  are  involved  in  notions  which  are  earlier 
than  philosophy.  What  philosophy  has  done  is  to  help  men 
to  think  their  way  through  them,  and  sometimes  out  of 
them,  or,  in  sheer  weariness,  by  them.  The  enthusiastic 
return  of  the  instrumentalist  to  "naive  realism''  is  that  of  a 
highly  sophisticated  wanderer,  and  its  full  meaning  can  be 
appreciated  only  by  those  who  have  likewise  wandered. 
Deliberate  abstinence  from  metaphysics  is  an  unnatural  and 
laborious  attainment,  to  achieve  which  requires  the  arduous 
training  of  philosophy. 

For,  in  the  second  place,  it  is  true  that  to  theorize  is  natural 
to  man.  Men  delight  in  theorizing,  in  taking  synoptic  views 
of  experience,  and  the  contemplative  mind  has  its  own 
rights, — and  duties.  A  philosophy  which  devotes  itself  to 
the  reflective  satisfaction  of  this  interest  in  theory  is  not 
"undemocratic,"  but  more  broadly  humane  than  one  which 
rejects  this  task.  Some  years  ago  a  book  was  written  in 
which  pragmatism  was  described  as  the  philosophy  of  a 
materialistic  democracy,  envying  and  suspecting  intellectual 
superiority,  and  bent  on  comfort  and  success  at  the  expense 
of  truth.  James  thereupon  characterized  the  book  as  a 
"sociological  romance."  Is  there  not  something  of  the 
sociological  romance  in  the  frequent  assumption  that  only 
instrumentalism  is  genuinely  democratic,  since  other  philos 
ophies  are  devoted  to  the  t aristocratic'  end  of  contemplation, 
and  scorn  to  concern  themselves  with  the  urgent  difficulties 
of  ordinary  men?  Philosophy  as  a  program  of  social  re 
form  is  not  a  new  thing  in  the  world,  and  it  is  the  business 
of  thought  to  enable  men  to  appreciate  the  good  they  already 
have  as  well  as  to  enable  them  to  bring  new  good  into  being. 
It  is  the  business  of  philosophy,  also,  to  raise  the  principles 
on  which  men  act  to  the  level  of  explicit  reflection  and  sys 
tem,  in  order  that  they  may  be  criticised  and  tested,  and 


222  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

also  in  order  that  the  ideal  achievement  of  one  generation 
may  be  preserved  for  the  generations  that  follow.  These 
are  all  human  interests,  and  their  successful  realization  can 
be  only  through  speculation  and  theory. 

It  is  characteristic  that  instrumentalism,  speaking  broadly, 
has  been  most  successful  in  the  field  of  ethics,  where  its 
methodology  is  practically  a  theory  of  the  subject  matter 
as  well.  No  system  which  omits  a  metaphysic  is  a  complete 
philosophy,  and  such  systems  in  the  past  have  never  pre 
served  their  equilibrium  against  the  normal  metaphysical 
impulse.  But  while  instrumentalism  in  its  present  form  is 
certainly  naturalistic,  Professor  Dewey  tells  us  that  it  neither 
will  nor  can  be  a  metaphysic.  Particular  explanations  of 
particular  facts  are  all  it  either  gives  or  requires.  "The  chief 
characteristic  trait  of  the  pragmatic  notion  of  reality  is  pre 
cisely  that  no  theory  of  Reality  in  general,  uberhaupt,  is 
possible  or  needed.  It  occupies  the  position  of  an  eman 
cipated  empiricism  or  a  thoroughgoing  naive  realism.  It 
finds  that  'reality'  is  a  denotative  term,  a  word  used  to  desig 
nate  indifferently  everything  that  happens.  .  .  .  Pragma 
tism  is  content  to  take  its  stand  with  science;  ...  for 
science  finds  all  such  events  to  be  subject-matter  of  descrip 
tion  and  inquiry. "  J  The  meaningless  problem  of  determin 
ing  the  real  by  way  of  contrast  with  the  unreal  is  thus  re 
jected;  but  along  with  it  goes  every  discrimination  between 
the  constituents  of  the  real  as  to  significance  for  a  general 
theory  of  reality.  In  fact,  there  is  no  such  theory;  the 
sciences  are  enough. 

Two  questions  arise  in  regard  to  this  refusal  to  be  meta 
physical:  (i)  Is  it  consistently  adhered  to?  (2)  Is  it  a  suffi 
cient  justification,  supposing  its  propriety  were  admitted, 
for  a  certain  noteworthy  gap  in  instrumentalism? 

Instrumentalism  takes  its  stand  with  the  sciences.  But 
among  the  sciences,  for  its  own  purposes  as  a  general  theory 
of  control,  it  finds  biology  especially  significant.  Now  the 
most  striking  characteristic  of  modern  biological  theory  is 
that  it  comprises  two  classes  of  ideas,  widely  different  in 
1  Creative  Intelligence,  p.  55. 


SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM  223 

nature  and  tendency.  To  the  one  class  belong  the  ideas  of 
organism  and  environment,  stimulus  and  response,  adapta 
tion  and  selection,  and  all  the  intellectual  apparatus  of  the 
evolution-hypothesis;  to  the  other  belong  Mendelian  deter 
minants,  unit-characters,  and  all  the  mechanics  of  heredity. 
The  latter  may  be  congenial  matter  for  the  contemplation 
of  an  analytic  realist;  but  they  have  no  special  appeal  for 
the  instrumentalist,  and  they  are  in  logical  contradiction 
with  any  genuine  evolution.  This  does  not  especially  per 
plex  the  working  biologist,  perhaps,  so  far  as  he  is  not  con 
cerned  with  ultimate  logical  consistency;  he  is  dealing  with 
particular  'events'  as  "subject-matter  of  description  and 
inquiry."  But  it  is  a  matter  of  vital  interest  for  the  instru 
mentalist,  and  he  does  not  hesitate  to  select  the  first  set  of 
ideas  as  his  categories,  because  they  enable  him  to  reflect 
ively  construe  experience,  while  the  other  set,  used  in  the 
same  inclusive  and  analogical  way,  do  not.  Now  what  is  this 
selective  use  of  categories,  so  far  as  it  goes,  but  the  method 
of  a  critically  speculative  metaphysics?  And  what  forbids 
us  to  push  it  farther,  to  recognize  frankly  the  limits  of 
naturalistic  explanation,  and  so  add  to  this  view  of  things 
the  peculiar  qualities  of  the  real  that  thought  reveals  as  it 
frees  itself  from  the  network  of  immediate  circumstance? 

I  come  in  conclusion  to  the  "noteworthy  gap"  mentioned 
above.  It  has  been  sometimes  objected  that  instrumentalism 
does  not  face  the  mind  and  body  problem;  that  the  reflex-arc 
theory  might  perhaps  state  the  conditions  under  which  in 
tellection  appears,  but  did  not  account  for  consciousness. 
Now  the  instrumentalist,  so  far  as  he  conducts  his  discussion 
with  the  idealist,  may  counter  with  the  remark  that  neither 
does  idealism  account  for  mind.  But  it  must  be  replied  that 
idealism  presupposes  mind  systematically,  which  is  a  very 
different  matter:  it  regards  reality  as  always  and  every 
where  involving  thought  as  well  as  things.  Thus,  making 
thought  an  ultimate  factor  in  experience,  Hegel  for  instance 
may  be  asked  what  work  or  place  is  left  for  individual  mind, 
perhaps;  or  he  may  be  asked  how  mind  and  body  are  related 
in  an  individual  conscious  organism.  Such  questions  may 


224  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

be  reasonably  addressed  to  the  objective  idealist;  but  he 
cannot  be  reasonably  asked  to  account  for  mind  in  general. 
But  this  is  just  what  instrumentalism  must  be  asked  to  do, 
since  it  systematically  refuses  to  presuppose  mind,  and 
recognizes  only  particular  cases,  so  to  speak,  of  mind  arising 
from  situations  in  which  there  was  no  mind  in  any  sense. 
And  this  is  just  the  question  which  instrumentalism  is  neces 
sarily  incapable  of  answering,  because  it  insists  on  remaining 
a  method  of  particular  cases,  and  relying  on  the  naturalistic 
explanation  of  these. 

These  statements  require  some  further  explanation.  Re 
flection,  as  the  instrumentalist  rightly  insists,  arises  in  situa 
tions  which  are  non-reflectional :  "situations  of  prizing  and 
aversion,  of  seeking  and  finding,  of  converse,  enjoyment  and 
suffering,  of  production  and  employment,  of  manipulation 
and  destruction."  Such  phrases,  the  use  of  the  term  'ex 
perience'  to  cover  the  whole  continuum  of  situations  and 
reflections,  and  the  description  of  these  situations  as  "social, 
affectional,  technological,  aesthetic,  and  so  on,"  apparently 
imply  that  another  form  of  consciousness  is  present  where 
reflection  is  not.  But  we  must  not  suppose  that  this  is  meant 
universally;  we  are  warned  against  such  an  understanding 
of  these  statements.  "Consciousness  is  only  a  very  small 
and  shifting  portion  of  experience.  .  .  .  In  the  experience, 
and  in  it  in  such  a  way  as  to  qualify  even  what  is  shiningly 
apparent,  are  all  the  physical  features  of  the  environment, 
extending  out  into  space  no  one  can  say  how  far,  and  all  the 
habits  and  interests,  extending  backward  and  forward  in 
time,  of  the  organism.  .  .  .  And  if  we  are  asked  why  not 
then  use  a  general  objective  term  like  'world,'  or  'environ 
ment,'  the  answer  is  that  the  word  'experience'  suggests 
something  indispensable  which  these  terms  omit:  namely,  an 
actual  focussing  of  the  world  at  one  point  in  a  focus  of  im 
mediate  shining  apparency."  1 

The  instrumentalist  use  of  the  term  'experience,'  then, 
does  not  connote  that  consciousness  is  present  even  when 
reflection  or  judgment  is  not;  but  it  means  rather  that  con- 

1  Quotations  from  Dewey,  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  pp.  2,  3,  6-7. 


SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM  225 

sciousness  is  present  somewhere  in  the  world,  and  that  the 
rest  of  the  world  is  in  ' dynamic  connection'  with  it.  There 
remains  the  question:  Is  consciousness  in  some  form  present 
sometimes  when  reflection  is  not?  In  other  words,  is  there 
such  a  thing  as  non-reflective,  "immediate"  consciousness? 
And,  as  far  as  Professor  Dewey  is  concerned,  the  answer 
seems,  at  first  glance,  to  be  plainly  affirmative.  The  pas 
sages  already  quoted  concerning  the  enrichment  of  subse 
quent  experience  by  reflection  which  appears  primarily  as 
control,  and  many  others  of  the  same  kind,  plainly  indicate 
this.1  In  fact,  the  ideas  of  tension,  conflict,  and  so  on,  as 
yet  unsolved,  but  stimulants  to  intellectual  activity,  connote 
such  non-reflective  consciousness.  And  if  we  have  some 
lingering  suspicion  that  its  status  is  left  uncertain,  and  that 
after  all  it  may  be  taken  as  physiological  behavior  with  no 
conscious  side,  these  may  be  removed  by  examining  such  a 
fuller  statement  of  instrumentalist  psychology  as  that  now 
given  by  Professor  Bode.2  It  is  there  made  plain  that  what 
is  essential  is  the  explanation  of  consciousness  as  an  organiza 
tion  of  behavior  with  regard  to  future  consequences:  "The 
rendering  of  future  stimulations  or  results  into  terms  of 
present  existence.  Consciousness  is  a  name  for  a  certain 
change  that  takes  place  in  the  stimulus;  or,  more  specif 
ically,  it  is  a  name  for  the  control  of  conduct  by  future  re 
sults  or  consequences."  This  applies  to  perception  as  well 
as  to  judgment,  "to  every  form  of  quality  and  relation."  3 

Consciousness  then  has  two  forms:  unreflective  and  re 
flective.  But  it  is  always  a  particular  activity  of  individual 
organic  adjustment,  and  judgment  is  simply  the  sort  of  ad 
justment  or  control  required  when  the  kind  of  response 
needed  is  as  yet  unknown.  It  is  worth  noticing,  also,  that 
there  is  a  very  pretty  correspondence  between  Professor 
Dewey's  account  of  judgment  and  Professor  Bode's  account 
of  consciousness,  so  far  as  the  latter  reinterprets  the  current 

1  Cf.,  for  example,  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  pp.  4,  23  (the  remark 
about  "imagination"),  62f. 

2  See  his  essay  in  Creative  Intelligence,  pp.  228-281. 

3  Ibid.,  pp.  243,  244. 


226  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

psychological  distinction  of  "  focus  and  margin."  What  judg 
ment  terminates  in  is  a  thing  known,  and  not  knowledge,  says 
Professor  Dewey;  what  is  at  the  focus  is  a  thing  in  the 
physical  world,  a  thing  perceived,  and  not  consciousness, 
says  Professor  Bode.  Consciousness  is  the  '  margin,'  where 
control  is  in  the  making,  where  the  stimulus  is  chang 
ing. 

As  it  stands,  then,  this  psychology  is  consistent  as  well  as 
acute;  there  are  certain  parallels  in  it  to  Hegel's  account  of 
subjective  mind  which  are  interesting,  but  must  be  omitted 
here.  My  present  question  is:  Is  this  psychology  a  sufficient 
account  of  mind?  It  confines  itself  to  the  topics  of  percep 
tion  and  of  judgment.  What  can  it  do,  at  one  extreme,  with 
feeling,  and  at  the  other,  with  the  recognition  of  other  minds, 
with  knowing  the  same  truth  as  others  do,  and  with  the  ac 
knowledgment  of  the  social  institutions  which  embody  com 
mon  interests  and  ideals?  What  can  it  do,  that  is,  with  en 
joyments  and  aversions?  And  how  can  it  account  for  the 
universal  and  the  social  in  conscious  experience,  and  for 
what  Hegel  called  ' objective  mind'? 

That  enjoyment  and  aversion  may  be  elements  in  control, 
or  results  of  control,  is  admitted.  On  the  theory  proposed, 
however,  they  can  be  elements  only  if  they  have  already 
been  results;  and  as  results  (that  is,  as  ' focal')  they  are  not 
consciousness.  One  may  be  ready  to  grant  the  truth  of 
James's  shrewd  remark  that  pleasures  and  pains  are  am 
biguous  things,  which  may  be  taken  as  either  *  physical'  or 
'psychical.'  But  to  take  them  as  ever  not  ' psychical'  at  all 
seems  absurd. 

The  second  question  is,  of  course,  a  more  serious  one.  At 
first  sight,  it  may  seem  surprising  that  it  should  be  asked. 
Is  instrumentalism,  which  makes  so  much  of  the  social,  in 
capable  of  really  recognizing  it,  compatibly  with  its  general 
theory?  The  answer  is:  Yes,  if  it  remains  naturalistic  and 
positivistic;  if  it  insists  on  regarding  everything  that  is  real 
as  a  particular  fact  or  event  in  the  physical  world.  Take 
the  character  of  my  friend,  for  instance.  It  is  something 
which  I  judge  and  infer;  but  it  is  even  more  something  which 


SOME  COMMENTS  ON  INSTRUMENTALISM  227 

I  sympathetically  appreciate.  It  is  good  for  what  it  is,  more 
than  for  what  it  does.  It  belongs  to  an  order  of  ideal  goods, 
which  rise  out  of  nature  but  are  not  physical;  and  my  adapta 
tion  or  response  to  it  must  take  place  by  an  inner  assimilation 
to  it.  It  is  no  event,  or  series  of  events,  though  it  may  be 
in  part  a  result  of  events,  and  a  cause  of  further  events. 
How  can  it  be  known,  on  the  account  of  the  instrumentalists' 
psychology,  for  which  mind  is  always  particular  reactions 
in  a  particular  organism? 

Or  again,  take  any  institution  of  organized  society,  such 
as  a  school  system.  It  is  the  product  of  human  wills  and 
purposes,  it  is  a  means  to  realize  certain  interests,  and  it 
makes  use  of  and  includes  physical  things  as  well  as  human 
acts.  But  what  holds  it  together,  maintains  it,  and  keeps  it 
going,  is  a  common  recognition  of  an  end  as  valuable.  This 
end  is  subject  to  revision  and  change;  but  for  the  most  part 
it  serves  as  a  standard  to  judge  by,  instead  of  a  problem  to 
judge  about.  How  is  it  known  as  a  common  end  ?  It  is  not, 
while  being  used  as  a  standard,  the  result  of  that  judgment; 
and  it  is  not,  of  course,  in  a  sensational  margin.  So  ap 
parently  it  is  not  in  'consciousness';  but  neither  is  it  any 
other  event  or  fact  in  nature. 

All  of  this  corresponds  to  the  remark  already  made  that 
thought  must  enable  us  to  know  and  appreciate  attained 
good  as  well  as  to  create  new;  or  again,  to  the  statement  that 
developed  social  control  involves  a  factor  which  is  at  once 
independent  of  that  particular  case  of  control,  and  also  not 
adequately  described  as  a  fact,  event,  or  thing  in  the  physical 
world.  For  what  happens  in  such  cases  as  these  is  no  pre- 
established  harmony,  but  a  unity  of  action  created  from 
within  by  a  common  recognition  of  a  common  good.  Nature 
thus  turns  out  to  be  more  than  its  first  appearance  as 
physical. 

Any  reader  who  has  followed  to  this  point  will,  I  hope, 
have  read  between  the  lines  of  the  objections  to  instrumenal- 
ism  an  acknowledgment  of  its  real  achievements.  The  con 
clusions  of  the  argument  may  be  summarily  stated  as  follows : 
First,  the  naturalism  of  instrumentalism,  as  it  stands,  is  at 


228  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

odds  with  its  insistence  on  moral  values;  second,  instru- 
mentalism  ought  to  subordinate  naturalism,  and  become 
whole-heartedly  metaphysical.  If  it  did  so,  it  would  make 
instrumentalism  itself  a  chapter  in  a  new  development  of 
idealism. 


PRAGMATISM  AND  THE  CORRESPONDENCE 
THEORY  OF  TRUTH 

ELLEN  BLISS  TALBOT 

THE  task  of  this  paper  is  to  consider  the  correspondence 
theory  as  contrasted  with  the  pragmatic  doctrine  of  the 
nature  of  truth.  In  the  main  its  purpose  is  defensive;  that 
is,  we  shall  be  concerned  chiefly  with  trying  to  show  that  the 
theory  in  question  is  not  in  quite  so  perilous  a  situation  as 
the  pragmatists  would  have  us  believe.  Further,  we  shall 
take  the  theory  in  itself,  free  from  entangling  alliances  with 
certain  other  doctrines  which  pragmatists  commonly,  but  I 
think  erroneously,  assume  to  be  a  necessary  part  of  it.  Chief 
among  these  are  the  doctrines  that  reality  is  a  unitary  whole, 
that  it  is  essentially  changeless,  and  that  it  is  an  all-inclusive 
spirit.  It  is  possible  to  be  in  doubt  with  regard  to  any  or 
all  of  these, — or  even  to  reject  them, — and  still  to  maintain 
that  what  we  mean  by  truth  is  the  agreement  of  thought 
with  reality;  and  it  is  with  this  latter  proposition  that  we 
are  here  concerned. 

In  trying,  then,  to  defend  the  correspondence  theory  we 
are  not  assuming  a  hostile  attitude  toward  all  features  of 
pragmatism,  and  the  question  whether  we  should  be  called 
'intellectualists'  will  depend  upon  the  definition  of  that 
term.  This  poor  word  has  fallen  upon  days  so  evil  that  one 
could  hardly  be  blamed  for  preferring  another  appellation; 
but  since  we  shall  need  in  this  discussion  a  name  for  those 
who  differ  from  the  pragmatists  chiefly  in  espousing  the 
correspondence  theory,  I  shall  use  the  term  'intellectualist' 
in  this  sense,  and  in  this  alone.1 

My  own  position,  then,  may  be  called  moderate  intel- 
lectualism.  I  heartily  assent  to  the  doctrine  that  change  is 

1  And  corresponding  with  it,  the  word  'intellectualism.' 


230  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

an  essential  feature  of  reality.1  In  an  important  sense  also 
I  should  agree  that  our  thinking  alters  reality.  And  finally, 
I  believe  that  all  thought  is  for  the  sake  of  some  end  (though 
I  may  not  be  in  full  agreement  with  pragmatism  as  to  the 
nature  of  this  end).  But  on  the  other  hand,  I  am  not  able 
to  accept  the  pragmatic  doctrine  of  truth;  I  believe  that  the 
truth  of  a  theory  consists,  not  in  its  successful  working,  but 
in  its  correspondence  with  reality.2 

The  first  thing  to  be  said  is,  that  if  the  controversy  as  to 
truth  is  simply  with  regard  to  the  particular  meaning  to  be 
given  to  a  certain  term,  no  sensible  person  would  think  it 
worth  while  to  carry  on  a  long  argument  about  it  with  the 
pragmatists.  We  all  believe,  I  presume,  that  there  is  such 
a  thing  as  the  successful  working  of  a  theory.  Some  of  us 
think  also  that  there  is  such  a  thing  as  the  agreement  of  a 
theory  with  a  reality  other  than  itself.  And  if  the  question 
is  merely  to  which  of  the  two  the  word  'truth'  shall  be  ap 
plied,  I,  for  my  part,  have  no  wish  to  quarrel  with  our  prag- 
matist  friends.  To  be  sure,  one  might  make  out  a  fair  case 
of  grievance  against  them  by  urging  that  for  many  genera 
tions  the  word  t truth'  has  been  used  to  connote  the  agree 
ment  of  a  judgment  with  reality,  and  that  even  if  they  are  in 
need  of  some  word  to  stand  for  'successful  working,'  this 
need  hardly  justifies  them  in  committing  highway  robbery 
and  forcibly  appropriating  a  term  in  which  some  other  con 
ception  has  good  property  rights.  One  might,  I  say,  make 
out  such  a  case.  But  not  being  of  a  litigious  disposition,  I 
am  not  inclined  to  quarrel  about  the  ownership  of  any  word. 
If  the  pragmatist  will  grant  that  the  utility  of  a  theory  and 
its  correspondence  with  reality  are  two  distinct  conceptions, 
both  valid  and  both  important,  I  for  one  shall  be  willing  to 
let  him  christen  his  infant  prodigy  'truth'  and  shall  set  out 
cheerfully  in  search  of  another  cognomen  for  the  now  name 
less  and  despised  offspring  of  intellectualism.  The  change 
would  indeed  have  some  unpleasant  consequences,  such  as 

1  Meaning  by  this,  that  whether  all  reality  is  in  process  of  change  or 
not,  at  least  some  large  and  important  realms  of  being  are. 

2  /.  e.,  with  the  particular  reality  with  which  it  professes  to  correspond. 


PRAGMATISM  AND  CORRESPONDENCE  231 

the  necessity  of  translating  into  the  new  terminology  most 
of  the  philosophical  literature  prior  to  the  year  1900.  But 
if  pragmatism  is  not  deterred  by  unfortunate  practical  con 
sequences,  who  is  intellectualism  that  she  should  raise  her 
voice  in  protest? 

If,  then,  the  dispute  were  simply  as  to  the  property  rights 
in  a  certain  philosophical  term,  I  should  have  no  interest 
in  it.  But  while  in  some  cases  it  looks  as  if  the  pragmatist 
were  arguing  merely  about  the  application  of  a  word,  there 
can  be  little  doubt  that  the  divergence  between  him  and  the 
intellectualist  is  usually  more  serious. 

As  a  preliminary  to  considering  the  nature  of  this  diver 
gence,  I  shall  try  to  say  what  I  mean  by  the  correspondence 
of  thought  with  reality.  And  in  order  to  avoid  needless  com 
plications,  let  us  refrain  from  assuming  any  reality  other  than 
experience.  The  'radical  empiricism*  of  Professor  James, 
the  'instrumentalism'  of  the  Chicago  School,  and  the 
' humanism'  of  Dr.  Schiller,  all  seem  to  involve  the  identifi 
cation  of  reality  with  experience.1  We  need  not  stop  to  ask 
whether  this  identification  is  really  essential  to  pragmatist 
doctrine,  nor  even  whether  it  is  correct.2  What  I  wish  to 
do  is  rather  to  point  out  that  even  if  it  is  true  that  there  is 
no  reality  other  than  experience,  it  does  not  follow  that  the 
conception  of  the  correspondence  of  thought  with  reality 
has  no  meaning.3  For  it  is  surely  still  conceivable  that  one 
portion  of  experience  may  profess  to  represent  or  correspond 
with  some  other  portion.  In  such  case,  the  portion  that 
professes  to  represent  is  called  the  '  thought/  and  the  other 
portion  the  ' reality'  (or  the  'object'). 

Now  it  may  be  conceded  to  the  pragmatists  that  it  is  not 
easy  to  say  just  what  we  mean  by  'representing'  or  'corre- 

1  And  apparently  with  experience  of  the  human  type,  if  not,  in  all  cases, 
with  human  experience. 

2  Certainly  we  may  grant  that  if  there  is  any  reality  wholly  unrelated  to 
experience  and  incapable  of  coming  into  relation  to  it,  there  is  no  occasion 
for  our  troubling  our  heads  about  it. 

3  Unless  what  is  meant  is  that  all  reality  is  my  present  experience;  and 
he  pragmatists  of  course  do  not  mean  this. 


232  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

spending.'  In  some  cases,  as  Professor  James  h'as  pointed 
out,  it  may,  without  any  great  stretching  of  the  term,  be 
called  *  copying.'  When,  for  example,  I  believe  myself  to 
remember  in  detail  a  former  experience  of  mine  and  to 
remember  it  in  terms  similar  to  that  of  the  original  experi 
ence,1  I  believe  that  my  present  thought  'copies'  that  earlier 
experience.  To  be  sure,  I  do  not  assume  that  it  is  altogether 
like  its  predecessor.  There  are  the  differences  in  time- 
setting,  the  differences  between  image  and  perception,  and 
still  others  that  need  not  be  mentioned  here.  But  although 
I  am  more  or  less  aware  of  these  differences,  still  I  believe, — 
when  I  say  that  I  'remember,' — that  my  present  experience 
is  what  may  fairly  be  called  a  copy  of  the  earlier  one,  just 
as  we  might  say  that  a  photograph  is  the  copy  of  a  landscape, 
in  spite  of  its  lack  of  color,  its  smaller  size,  and  so  on.  When 
we  say  that  my  memory  copies  that  earlier  experience,  we 
mean  that  it  is  like  it  in  certain  important  points,  though 
unlike  it  in  others. 

But  also  I  may  be  ready  to  say  that  my  present  idea  agrees 
with  my  past  experience,  even  though  I  am  aware  that  the 
two  are  quite  different  in  their  terms.  Suppose,  for  example, 
that  I  profess  to  remember  the  substance  of  something  that 
you  said  to  me  months  ago.  I  may  not  recall  the  sound  of 
your  voice,  as  you  spoke,  nor  the  expression  of  your  face; 
I  may  not  be  sure  of  the  particular  words  that  you  used. 
Yet  I  insist  that  my  memory  of  that  past  event  is  accurate. 
Why?  Because  I  believe  that  the  words  in  terms  of  which 
I  am  now  thinking  have  a  meaning  similar  to  that  of  the 
words  that  you  employed.  That  is,  I  insist  that  my  thought 
corresponds  with  that  past  reality  because  the  two  are  alike 
in  meaning. 

It  is  clear,  then,  that  when  we  assume  the  correspondence 
of  our  thought  with  something  other  than  itself,  the  similar 
ity  may  be  of  various  sorts.  But  in  each  case  the  two  are 
supposed  to  agree  in  some  respect  that  is  important  for  the 
purpose  involved.  If  I  am  trying  in  vain  to  recall  the  sub- 

1  /.  e.j  to  remember  in  visual  terms  what  was  originally  visual  experience, 
in  auditory  terms  what  was  originally  auditory,  and  so  forth. 


PRAGMATISM  AND  CORRESPONDENCE  233 

stance  of  what  you  said  on  that  past  occasion,  it  boots  little 
that  I  can  remember  where  you  sat,  how  you  looked,  and 
how  your  voice  sounded.  For  my  thought  does  not  agree 
with  its  reality  in  the  respect  in  which  it  means  to  agree;  and 
so  long  as  it  does  not  do  this  it  is  futile.  When  we  say  that 
a  judgment  is  true,  we  mean  that  it  agrees  with  some  par 
ticular  portion  of  reality  in  the  respect  in  which  it  intends 
to  agree. 

Having  shown  what  we  understand  by  correspondence,  we 
may  now  try  to  offer  some  defense  of  the  conception.  I  have 
sa'id  that  even  if  we  assume  that  there  is  no  reality  other 
than  experience,  it  is  still  conceivable  that  one  portion  of 
experience  may  profess  to  correspond  with  some  other 
portion.  Now  I  submit  that  this  which  I  have  declared  con 
ceivable  is  something  that  on  the  face  of  it  seems  also  to  be. 
It  certainly  seems  as  if  there  were  parts  of  our  experience 
that  assume  to  correspond  with  something  other  than  them 
selves.  As  has  already  been  suggested,  it  is  not  necessary 
for  us  to  decide  here  whether  that  'other'  is  also  in  every  case 
a  portion  of  experience.  We  are  trying  to  establish  the 
validity  of  the  conception  of  correspondence.  And  for  that 
purpose  it  does  not  matter  whether  the  correspondence  be 
between  a  present  and  a  past  experience  of  mine,  between 
my  experience  and  yours,  between  my  experience  and  that 
of  'the  Absolute,'  or  finally  between  my  experience  and  a 
'physical  object.' 

This,  then,  is  my  first  contention,  that  thought  professes 
to  agree  with  some  reality  other  than  itself.  And  my  second 
is  that  there  is  a  reality  other  than  thought, — that  is,  than 
a  particular  thought, — and  that  therefore  the  question 
whether  a  particular  thought  does  or  does  not  agree  with  its 
reality  1  is  not  meaningless. 

As  to  the  first  of  these  two  points,  the  question  is  this: 
When  we  form  a  theory,  do  we  believe  ourselves  to  be  making 
a  plan  of  action,2  or  on  the  contrary  to  be  making  some  as- 

1  /.  e.j  the  reality  with  which  it  means  to  agree. 

'2  The  pragmatists  usually  alternate,  I  think,  between  the  two  views 
that  a  theory  is  a  plan  of  action  and  that  it  is  the  anticipation  of  conse- 


234  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

sertion  about  the  nature  of  reality?  To  this  the  ordinary 
man  would  reply,  I  think,  that  a  plan  of  action  is  one  thing 
and  a  theory  another,  and  that  when  he  makes  a  theory  he  in 
tends  to  make  some  assertion  about  the  nature  of  reality. 
For  example,  the  physician  to  whom  you  recount  your  symp 
toms  tells  you  that  you  have  appendicitis.  Now  it  may 
quite  well  be  that  he  has  a  plan  of  action, — either  medical 
treatment  or  surgery;  let  us  hope  that  he  has,  since  obviously 
something  ought  to  be  done.  And  further  it  may  quite  well 
be  that  his  plan  is  vitally  related  to  his  theory;  let  us  hope 
that  this  also  is  the  case.  Still  it  does  not  follow  that  the 
plan  and  the  theory  are  identical.  And  that  they  are  not  one 
and  the  same  thing  for  the  ordinary  man  seems  to  me  clear. 

And  not  only  is  this  true  of  the  non-scientific  minds,  which 
form  the  greater  part  of  mankind,  but  it  seems  also  to  be 
true  of  the  majority  of  scientists.  The  scientific  man  may 
indeed  hold  that  most  of  our  theories, — even  of  the  best 
ones, — fail  to  correspond  perfectly  with  reality.  But  if  he 
believes  this,  he  believes  at  the  same  time  that  most  of  our 
theories  are  not  completely  true.  With  comparatively  few 
exceptions,  I  think,  the  scientist  still  means  by  truth  what 
ordinary  folk  mean.  And  in  saying  this  I  am  not  unmindful 
of  the  pragmatist's  contention  that  his  notion  of  truth  is 
that  of  the  scientist.  It  seems  to  me,  however,  that  this 
assertion  still  remains  to  be  proved.1 

quences.  But  inasmuch  as  the  consequences  in  question  are  the  conse 
quences  of  the  action,  this  wavering  is  not  altogether  unnatural. 

1  E.  g.,  Dr.  Schiller  says,  "The  physicist  .  .  .  more  and  more  clearly 
sees  both  that  he  does  not  know  what  'matter'  ultimately  is,  and  that  for 
the  purposes  of  his  science  he  does  not  need  to  know,  so  long  as  the  term 
stands  for  something  the  behavior  of  which  he  can  calculate."  "Axioms 
as  Postulates,"  in  Personal  Idealism,  1902,  p.  55.  Yet,  I  reply,  physicists 
still  seem  tremendously  interested  in  the  question  what  matter  is  and  are 
ever  and  anon  formulating  new  theories  as  to  its  constitution,  in  an  effort, 
apparently,  to  get  a  description  that  shall  come  nearer  to  the  reality  than 
any  hitherto  proposed.  It  is  doubtless  true  that  there  are  physicists  who 
are  not  interested  in  this  question;  but  in  view  of  the  recent  work  that 
has  been  done  I  cannot  see  how  any  one  can  think  that  this  represents  the 
attitude  of  the  majority  of  physicists. 

That  science,  at  least  until  the  most  recent  times,  conceived  of  truth 


PRAGMATISM  AND  CORRESPONDENCE  235 

But  in  insisting  that  both  ordinary  folk  and  many  scien 
tists  accept  the  notion  of  correspondence  as  valid,  we  are 
dwelling  upon  a  relatively  unimportant  matter.  For  the 
pragmatist  might  concede  the  point  and  still  urge  that  this 
widespread  belief  is  erroneous.  This  brings  us,  however,  to 
the  second  of  my  two  contentions.  For  if  you  say  that  my 
thought  believes  itself  to  be  making  statements  about  real 
ity,  but  is  actually  planning  and  initiating  some  operation 
or  other,  your  assertion,  it  would  seem,  must  rest  upon  the 
conviction  that  'correspondence  with  reality'  is  a  meaningless 
phrase.  We  may  pass  on,  then,  to  our  second  thesis,  namely, 
that  there  is  something  other  than  itself  to  which  a  particular 
thought  points  and  that  consequently  there  is  meaning  in 
the  question  whether  the  thought  agrees  with  this  reality. 

To  this,  three  important  objections  seem  to  have  been 
made  by  the  pragmatists:  (i)  that  even  if  the  agreement  in 
question  is  conceivable,  it  is  of  no  consequence  because  all 
that  we  ever  care  for  is  the  successful  working  of  our  theory; 
(2)  that  even  if  there  were  agreement  of  our  thought  with 
reality,  we  could  never  know  in  a  particular  case  whether 
we  had  attained  it;  and  (3)  that  the  notion  of  correspondence 
is  meaningless  because  there  is  no  reality  apart  from  thought 

as  the  correspondence  of  our  judgments  with  reality  seems  to  have  been 
clearly  recognized  by  Professor  James  himself  (cf.  Pragmatism,  1907,  p.  56). 
And  even  when  he  goes  on  to  define  what  he  believes  to  be  the  attitude  of 
contemporary  science,  I  cannot  see  that  his  account  excludes  the  concep 
tion  of  correspondence  as  I  have  described  it.  "As  the  sciences  have  de 
veloped  farther,"  he  says,  "the  notion  has  gained  ground  that  most,  per 
haps  all,  of  our  laws  are  only  approximations.  ['To  what?'  one  is  tempted 
to  ask.]  .  .  .  Investigators  have  become  accustomed  to  the  notion  that  no 
theory  is  absolutely  a  transcript  of  reality,  but  that  any  one  of  them  may 
from  some  point  of  view  be  useful.  Their  great  use  is  to  summarize  old 
facts  and  to  lead  to  new  ones.  They  are  only  a  man-made  language,  .  .  . 
in  which  we  write  our  reports  of  nature"  (ibid.,  pp.  561.).  Certainly,  but 
we  still  write  our  reports  of  nature.  And  we  still  maintain,  when  we 
formulate  a  scientific  theory,  that  although  it  may  not  be,  and  may  not 
profess  to  be,  "absolutely  a  transcript  of  reality,"  it  is  like  reality  in  the 
respect  in  which  it  undertakes  to  be  like  it.  And  whenever  we  have  reason 
to  think  that  it  is  not  like  reality  in  this  respect,  we  say,  "I  was  mistaken; 
my  theory  is  not  true  (or  not  completely  true)." 


236  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

in  the  sense  which  the  intellectualist  assumes.  Let  us  take 
these  objections  in  order. 

(i)  That  all  thought  is  purposive  in  character,  that  one 
never  puts  oneself  to  the  trouble  of  thinking  except  for  the 
sake  of  some  end,  is  at  present  seldom  denied.  And  the 
unanimity  upon  this  point  is  in  large  measure  due  to  the  in 
fluence  of  the  pragmatists.  For  while  they  were  not  the 
first  to  show  that  thinking  presupposes  an  end,  the  vigor  and 
persuasiveness  with  which  they  have  preached  the  doctrine 
have  had  much  to  do  with  winning  adherents  to  it.  But  to 
admit  that  thinking  is  purposive  is  not  necessarily  to  grant 
that  when  we  frame  a  theory  our  interest  is  confined  to  its 
practical  consequences.  The  question  hinges,  of  course,  upon 
the  meaning  of  the  word  '  practical,'  and  about  this  there 
has  been  vigorous  debate.  I  shall  try  to  state  my  own  posi 
tion  as  clearly  as  I  can. 

There  is,  of  course,  no  question  that  in  many  cases  our  sole 
concern  is  with  the  successful  working  of  our  theory:  what 
we  are  after  is  practical  results,  and  given  these  we  have  no 
further  interest  in  the  matter.  If,  for  example,  I  have  started 
out  to  walk  to  a  certain  spot  and  can  save  myself  a  detour 
by  crossing  an  ice-covered  pond,  the  question  whether  the 
ice  is  strong  enough  to  bear  my  weight  is  one  whose  im 
portance  for  me  is  purely  practical.  All  that  I  care  for  is  to 
be  able  to  shorten  my  walk  without  subjecting  myself  to 
an  icy  wetting  and  to  other  consequences  that  might  be  even 
more  unpleasant.  But  while  there  are  many  cases  of  this 
sort,  in  which  we  care  only  that  our  theory  shall  work,  there 
are  others  in  which  our  desire  seems  to  be  for  truth  in  an 
other  sense.  We  want  to  be  assured  that  our  thought  corre 
sponds  with  the  reality  that  it  professes  to  stand  for;  in 
other  words  we  want  knowledge  for  the  sake  of  knowledge. 

Why  men  are  so  constituted  that  they  wish  to  understand 
for  no  other  reason  than  that  they  wish  to  understand  may  not 
be  easy  to  explain  in  detail.  But  that  they  are  so  constituted 
seems  to  be  shown  by  observation  and  experience.  And  it 
can  hardly  be  denied  that  the  existence  of  the  instinct,  if 
instinct  it  be,  justifies  itself  from  the  point  of  view  of  utility. 


PRAGMATISM  AND  CORRESPONDENCE  237 

It  is  not  difficult  to  see  that  it  may  often  be  highly  desirable 
that  a  man  should  want  knowledge  solely  for  its  own  sake. 
That  such  a  desire  has  been  the  motive  of  most  of  our  philo 
sophical  thinking  may  not  seem  to  all  an  indication  of  its 
utility;  but  that  it  has  also  been  the  source  of  a  large  part 
of  our  scientific  achievement  can  hardly  be  denied.  Pure 
science  seems  usually  to  have  been  inspired,  not  by  the 
desire  to  control  reality,  but  by  the  desire  to  understand  it. 
And  this  has  often  been  the  case  even  when  the  final  outcome 
of  the  scientific  activity  has  been  of  great  practical  im 
portance.  Just  as  happiness  is  more  likely  to  come  as  a  by 
product  than  as  the  result  of  a  deliberate  effort  to  gain  it,  so 
practical  benefits  of  the  highest  order  are  often  won  for  the 
race  by  men  whose  powers  have  all  been  given  to  the  quest 
of  something  quite  other  than  practical  benefits  of  any  sort. 

(2)  The  second  objection  is  that  even  if  the  conception 
of  the  agreement  of  thought  with  reality  is  admissible,  still 
we  cannot  know  in  any  particular  case  whether  or  not  this 
agreement  exists,  because  we  cannot  get  the  reality  and  the 
thought  apart  from  each  other  so  as  to  compare  them.1  To 
this  the  intellectualist  commonly  replies  that  successful 
working,  in  the  broad  sense,  is  the  best  indication  that  we 
have  of  the  correspondence  of  our  thought  with  reality. 
The  theory  is  to  be  tested  by  the  way  in  which  it  works, 
and  its  success  is  a  sign  of  its  truth. 

As  a  matter  of  fact  the  intellectualist  has  as  good  means 
of  knowing  whether  and  to  what  extent  his  theory  is  true 
as  the  pragmatist  has.  For  strictly  speaking,  the  pragmatist 
himself  cannot  have  absolute  assurance  of  the  truth  of  a 
theory.  Successful  working,  he  tells  us,  constitutes  truth. 
But  when  we  ask,  "Successful  for  whom?"  and  "Successful 
for  how  long?"  we  are  usually  told  that  only  those  theories 
are  true  that  work  on  the  whole  and  in  the  long  run.2  Now  it 

1  Cf.  Schiller,  Humanism,  1903,  p.  46. 

2  This  statement  is  correct,  I  think,  so  far  as  most  pragmatists  are  con 
cerned.    And  in  the  cases  in  which  it  is  not  correct,  there  is  the  difficulty 
that  apparently  any  theory  that  works  well  for  any  one  must  be  called 
true.    This  difficulty  is  often  to  some  extent  hidden  by  the  useful, — and 
hence,  of  course,  unimpeachable, — phrase,  "in  so  far  forth." 


238  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

is  clear  that  no  one  can  be  sure  that  a  given  theory  will  work 
on  the  whole  and  in  the  long  run;  for  'the  whole'  and  'the 
long  run'  are  quite  as  inaccessible  to  the  pragmatist  as 
'reality'  is  to  the  intellectualist.  In  other  words,  for  prag 
matist  and  intellectualist  alike  the  completely  true  is  the 
ideal,  which  in  a  given  case  certainly  cannot  be  known  to 
have  been  attained  and  in  all  probability  has  not  been 
attained. 

The  pragmatist  might  contend  that  in  thus  appealing  to 
practical  consequences  the  intellectualists  are  stealing  his 
thunder.  But  to  this  we  can  reply  that  successful  working 
has  been  regarded  as  the  test  of  truth  throughout  the  history 
of  modern  science,  and  that  at  least  until  the  most  recent 
times  modern  science  has  conceived  of  truth  as  agreement 
with  reality.1  And  since  intellectualism  in  the  person  of  the 
scientist  has  for  centuries  been  testing  its  theories  by  the 
appeal  to  facts,  we  can  hardly  deny  the  right  of  the  intel 
lectualist  philosopher  to  make  use  of  the  same  criterion. 

But  there  is  another  ground  on  which  one  might  object 
to  our  contention  that  the  intellectualist  can  test  the  truth 
of  his  theory  by  its  consequences.  How,  it  may  be  asked, 
can  one  who  conceives  of  truth  as  agreement  know  that  the 
successful  working  of  a  theory  is  in  any  degree  an  indication 
of  its  correspondence  with  reality?  That  a  given  theory  is 
at  present  working  fairly  well,  in  the  limited  field  in  which 
we  are  attempting  to  apply  it,  we  can  often  know  through 
observation,  through  the  experience  of  its  consequences. 
Pragmatism,  then,  because  it  identifies  truth  with  successful 
working  can  at  least  say  that  the  theory  is  true  "in  so  far 
forth."  But  how  can  intellectualism  be  sure  that  successful 
working,  either  now  or  through  a  long  period,  points  to 
even  a  partial  agreement  with  reality?  Why  may  it  not  as 
well  be, — for  aught  we  know, — that  theories  that  work  ill 
are  the  ones  that  agree  with  reality,  or  again  that  there  is  no 
connection  of  any  sort  between  'working'  and  'agreement'? 

1  That  this  conception  of  truth  was  held  by  practically  all  scientists  until 
our  own  day  has  been  recognized  by  Professor  James,  as  was  pointed  out 
above. 


PRAGMATISM  AND  CORRESPONDENCE  239 

To  this  we  may  reply  as  follows.  When  you  urge  that  in- 
tellectualism  cannot  know  that  successful  working  betokens 
agreement  with  reality,  you  of  course  assume,  for  the  sake 
of  the  argument,  that  some  theories  do  agree, — fairly  well,— 
with  reality  and  that  others  do  not.  Now  on  the  basis  of  this 
assumption,  how  can  there  be  doubt  in  the  mind  of  anyone 
that,  in  general,  theories  that  agree  will  be  successful,  when 
tried  out,  and  those  that  do  not  agree  will  be  unsuccessful? 
To  suppose  anything  else  would  be  to  assume  such  a  divorce 
between  reality  and  our  experience  as  no  one  to-day, — prag- 
matist,  moderate  intellectualist,  or  absolutist, — could  con 
template  as  a  possibility.  The  intellectualist,  then,  may 
assert  as  confidently  as  the  pragmatist  that  the  success 
ful  working  of  his  theory  gives  reason  for  believing  in  its 
truth. 

(3)  We  come  finally  to  the  third  objection  to  the  doctrine 
of  correspondence, — namely,  that  the  notion  of  agreement 
is  nonsense  because  there  is  no  such  distinction  between 
reality  and  our  thought  as  the  conception  implies.  This 
objection  is  voiced  by  Professor  Dewey  and  Professor  Moore 
in  their  protests  against  what  the  latter  calls  "the  private- 
consciousness-outer-reality  view  of  thought."  l 

My  reply  to  this  objection  must  begin  by  assenting  to  a 
large  part  of  what  I  understand  Professor  Dewey  and  Pro 
fessor  Moore  to  be  contending  for.  The  vital  relation  of  our 
thought  with  reality  must  be  granted  by  the  intellectualist, 
if  he  maintains  that  we  can  know  anything  at  all  about  the 
real,  and  also  if  he  urges  that  the  successful  working  of  a 
theory  is  a  sign  of  its  truth.  Both  these  doctrines  imply 
that  thought  is  in  intimate  contact  with  reality.  And  further 
I  agree  that  thought  "operates  within  reality."  For  in  the 
first  place  it  is  an  integral  part  of  reality;  every  act  of  think 
ing  is  itself  real.  And  in  the  second  place  thought, — itself  a 

1  For  Professor  Moore's  discussion  see  Pragmatism  and  Its  Critics, 
pp.  225ff.  Cf.  Professor  Dewey's  articles  on  "The  Experimental  Theory 
of  Knowledge,"  Mind,  N.  S.,  Vol.  XV,  1906,  pp.  293$.,  and  "The  Logical 
Character  of  Ideas,"  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific 
Methods,  Vol.  V,  1908,  pp.  375ff. 


240  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

part   of    reality, — issues    in    action,   which   modifies    other 
parts. 

But  while  I  believe  that  every  thought  is  itself  a  part  of 
reality  and  that  through  its  connection  with  volition  it  may 
indirectly  alter  other  parts,  I  do  not  see  what  is  to  be  gained 
by  confusing  the  cognitive  function  with  the  alterative. 
And  it  is  with  the  cognitive  that  we  are  here  concerned.  Now 
in  order  that  we  may  understand  this  function  or  even  admit 
its  possibility,  we  must  assume,  I  have  said,  that  thinking 
is  intimately  connected  with  the  rest  of  reality.  Thought 
reaches  out  and  lays  hold  upon  some  portion  of  the  real 
whenever  we  succeed  in  forming  an  approximately  correct 
theory.  That  this  reaching  out  and  laying  hold, — this  which 
the  intellectualist  is  fond  of  calling  'the  self-transcending 
function  of  thought/ — is  possible  at  all  means  that  thinking 
is  not  cut  off  from  the  rest  of  what  is,  that  we  do  not  live 
in  a  world  of  phenomena,  to  be  sharply  distinguished  from 
another  world  of  things-in-themselves.1 

But  assuming  thus,  as  we  must,  that  thinking  and  the 
rest  of  reality  are  closely  connected,  we  do  not  necessarily 
assume  that  they  are  connected  in  such  a  way  that  the  notion 
of  their  agreement  is  meaningless.  And  when  we  ask  why, 
on  the  other  hand,  this  notion  seems  to  be  required,  I  think 
the  simplest  answer  is  that  it  is  required  by  the  conception 
of  other  persons.  What  I  mean  is  this.  Professor  Dewey, 
for  example,  recognizes  that  in  a  sense  we  must  distinguish 
between  a  thought  and  the  reality  that  it  means;  that  is, 
they  may  be  distinguished  as  two  factors  in  a  total  situation. 
But  when  we  ask  what  we  are  to  understand  by  'thought's 
meaning  an  object,'  we  are  told  that  the  thought  is  an 

1  But  here  the  pragmatist  may  protest  that  whereas  he  has  good  right  to 
assert  the  vital  connection  of  thought  with  its  object,  the  intellectualist 
has  no  such  right.  I  reply  that  all  argument  presupposes  the  possibility  of 
the  cognitive  function,  and  that  any  one  who  admits  its  possibility  must 
deny  that  there  is  an  impassable  gulf  between  thought  and  reality.  Hence 
the  pragmatist  cannot  say,  even  to  the  intellectualist,  How  do  you  know 
that  thought  can  lay  hold  upon  the  real?  For  to  ask  the  question  is  to 
admit  the  possibility  of  such  a  divorce  between  these  two  as  would  make 
the  asking  of  all  questions  futile. 


PRAGMATISM  AND  CORRESPONDENCE  241 

expectation  of  and  demand  for  certain  experiences  that 
are  to  result  from  that  manipulating  (of  the  situation) 
which  grows  out  of  and  is  continuous  with  the  think 
ing.1 

Now  in  cases  like  the  one  that  Professor  Dewey  uses  for 
illustration, — where  the  thought  is  a  smell  and  the  object 
a  rose, — one  might  let  his  statement  pass  without  trying  to 
challenge  it.2  But  suppose  that  the  object  is  a  person  and 
the  thought  is  a  belief,  on  the  part  of  some  one  else,  that  this 
person  is  in  a  state  of  deep  grief.  I  submit  that  in  this  case 
at  least, — whatever  may  be  true  of  odors  and  roses, — we  are 
describing  the  situation  falsely  when  we  say  that  my  belief 
that  you  are  in  sorrow  is  an  expectation  of  experiences  of 
mine  that  are  to  ensue  upon  the  operation  of  that  belief. 
It  may  be  that  there  will  be  experiences  and  that  they  will 
be  such  as  to  verify  my  conjecture.  But  to  say  that  my  belief 
is  the  expectation  of  these  and  that  its  truth  consists  in  their 
coming  to  pass  is  to  ignore  your  existence  as  a  person.  For 
whether  a  rose  is  anything  in  its  own  right  or  not, — a  ques 
tion  that  we  need  not  discuss  here, — a  person,  if  there  be 
any  such,  is  something  in  his  own  right.  And  either  we 
should  say  that  it  is  doubtful  whether  there  are  persons,  or 
we  should  see  to  it  that  our  theory  of  the  nature  of  truth 
leaves  room  for  them. 

The  pragmatists,  as  we  know,  protest  that  it  is  an  act 
of  injustice  to  accuse  them  of  solipsism.  Professor  Moore, 
for  example,  reminds  us  of  their  "social  conception  of  con- 

1  In  Professor  Dewey's  own  words,  the  "cognitional"  experience  is 
"fated  or  charged  with  the  sense  of  the  possibility  of  a  fulfilment"  of  a 
certain  character.  It  "is  aware  of  something  else  which  it  means,  which 
it  intends  to  effect  through  an  operation  which  it  incites  and  without  which 
its  own  presence  is  abortive."  "The  Experimental  Theory  of  Knowledge," 
Mind,  N.  S.,  Vol.  XV,  1906,  p.  299.  It  is  true  that  Professor  Dewey  calls  this 
"cognitional  experience"  a  "knowledge"  (rather  than  judgment  or  belief); 
but  he  explains  that  he  is  using  the  word  *  knowledge'  in  the  sense  of  some 
thing  that  precedes  verification,  something  that  is  "hypothetical,  lacking 
in  assurance,  in  categorical  certainty."  Ibid.,  p.  298. 

2 1  do  not  mean  to  say  that  there  is  not  good  ground  for  challeng 
ing  it. 


242  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

sciousness"  and  joins  Professor  Dewey  in  urging  that  the 
charge  of  solipsism  can  be  established  only  if  we  make  the 
false  assumption  that  pragmatism  accepts  such  antiquated 
notions  as  "private  stream  of  consciousness/'  " other  real 
ities,"  and  "correspondence"  between  these  two.  But  I 
reply  that  unless  you  admit,  in  a  case  such  as  I  have  sup 
posed,  a  consciousness  in  some  degree  private,  and  other 
reality  in  relation  to  it,  and  the  possibility  of  correspondence 
between  these  two,  I  cannot  see  that  you  are  admitting  the 
reality  of  other  persons  at  all.  And  if  you  are  not,  what  shall 
it  profit  you  to  insist  that  your  "conception  of  conscious 
ness"  is  "social"? 

I  do  not,  of  course,  suppose  that  pragmatism  intends  to 
deny  the  reality  of  *  persons.'    It  seems  to  me,  however,  that 
the  failure  of  the  pragmatic  theory  of  truth  is  most  obvious 
when  we  try  to  apply  it  to  a  case  in  which  one  person  makes 
some  judgment  about  another  person.    When  I  have  an  ex 
perience  of  smell  and  exclaim,  "There  must  be  a  rose  in  this 
room!"  one  might  possibly  say  *  that  ultimately  this  means 
merely,  "If  I  act  thus  and  so,  I  shall  have  such  and  such 
experiences."  2     But  when   I   say,    "There   is   some   other 
person  in  this  room!"  this  cannot  be  interpreted  as  meaning 
merely,  "If  I  act  thus  and  so,  I  shall  have  such  and  such 
experiences."     For  when  I  assert  the  presence  of  another 
person,  I  not  only  imply  that  if  I  do  certain  things  I  shall 
have  experiences  of  a  certain  sort;  I  also  imply  that  I  stand 
in  relation  to  a  reality  over  and  above  any  experiences  of 
mine,  past,  present,  or  future:  I  assert  the  reality  of  that 

I 1  do  not  mean  that  this  expresses  my  own  belief  in  the  matter,  but 
simply  that  it  is  a  position  that  one  might  conceivably  take. 

2 1  take  ' thought'  here  as  meaning  for  the  pragmatist  the  anticipation 
of  consequences  and  leave  out  of  account  the  fact  that  he  also  often  de 
scribes  it  as  a  plan  for  bringing  these  consequences  to  pass.  I  do  this  be 
cause  I  can  put  more  simply  the  point  that  I  wish  to  make,  if  I  select  that 
aspect  of  the  pragmatic  conception  which  seems  to  me  the  less  open  to 
objection.  For  one  might  be  willing  to  interpret  the  judgment,  "There  is 
a  rose  in  this  room,"  as  meaning,  "If  I  act  thus  and  so,  I  shall  have  such 
experiences,"  and  yet  dissent  from  the  other  interpretation,  "I  purpose  to 
act  in  this  way  in  order  that  I  may  have  these  experiences." 


PRAGMATISM  AND  CORRESPONDENCE  243 

which,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  not  only  is  not,  but  never  can  be, 
my  experience.1 

To  this,  one  must  suppose,  Professor  Dewey  would  reply 
that  in  talking  thus  of  what  is  and  what  is  not  'my'  expe 
rience  I  am  begging  the  question:  I  first  take  for  granted  that 
he  admits  my  private  consciousness  and  then  accuse  him  of 
denying  the  other  private  consciousness,  whereas  in  fact  he 
rejects  them  both.  His  point  would  be  well  taken,  but  the 
objection  can  be  obviated  by  a  slight  change  in  our  previous 
statement.  Instead  of  saying  that  Professor  Dewey's  con 
ception  of  the  nature  of  thinking  seems  to  ignore  the  reality 
of  other  persons  than  the  thinker,  we  should  have  said  that 
it  seems  to  ignore  the  reality  of  all  persons.  My  criticism, 
then,  of  the  pragmatist's  rejection  of  the  notion  of  corre 
spondence,  more  accurately  put,  is  this.  Such  members  of 
the  pragmatic  fold  as  would  admit  the  fitness  of  the  phrase 
'my  experience,'  2  in  the  case  before  us,  cannot  deny  the 
validity  of  the  conception  of  correspondence  without  vir 
tually  ignoring  the  reality  of  that  other  person  to  whom  my 
judgment  refers.  And  this  seems  to  furnish  some  justifica 
tion  for  the  charge  that  pragmatism  involves  solipsism.  If, 
however,  a  pragmatist,  wishing  to  prove  that  he  is  not  a 
solipsist,  points  triumphantly  to  his  rejection  of  the  "private- 
consciousness-outer-reality  view  of  thought,"  we  can  answer 
that  he  has  avoided  the  mistake  of  ignoring  the  reality  of 
other  persons  only  by  the  device  of  ignoring  the  reality  of 
all  persons.  And  the  single  point  in  this  that  is  to  his  credit 
is  its  absolute  impartiality. 

With  this  I  must  bring  my  discussion  of  the  correspondence 
theory  to  a  close.  But  I  am  unwilling  to  stop  without  a  word 
of  explanation  as  to  my  attitude  in  the  last  argument.  It  is 
not,  in  its  intent,  an  argumentum  ad  populum.  In  raising 

1  That  it  is  possible  for  a  judgment  to  mean  something  that  can  never 
be  a  part  of  "the  same  continuous  experience  series"  with  itself  is  well 
brought  out  by  Professor  Rogers  in  his  "Statement  of  Epistemological 
Dualism,"  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific  Methods, 
Vol.  XIII,  1916,  p.  181. 

2 1  venture  to  think  that  there  are  some. 


244  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  objection  that  Professor  Dewey's  theory  seems  to  ignore 
the  existence  of  persons,  I  do  not  mean  to  imply  that  the 
reason  why  this  should  not  be  ignored  is  that  personality  is 
important  or  sacred,  though  in  another  connection  I  should 
not  hesitate  to  express  my  conviction  that  it  is  both  important 
and  sacred.1  The  only  reason  why  a  theory  of  knowledge 
should  not  ignore  persons,  it  seems  to  me,  is  that  to  do  so 
is  to  give  a  false  account  of  our  experience.  That  some  ex 
perience  at  any  rate,  namely,  that  which  I  designate  by 
calling  it  'mine,'  is  personal, — that  it  is,  at  the  very  least,2 
a  centralized  whole  of  functions  which  are  not  adequately 
described  by  calling  them  'intra-organic,' — this,  I  am  old- 
fashioned  enough  to  be  willing  to  say,  seems  certain  if  any 
thing  at  all  is  certain.  And  it  is  this  centralized  character, 
which  I  express  when  I  say  'my'  experience,  that  the  "ex 
perimental  theory  of  knowledge,"  like  some  other  new 
theories,  seems  to  ignore. 

1  A  conviction  which  doubtless  many  pragmatists  share. 
2 1  think  that  we  might  say  somewhat  more  than  this,  but  I  wish  to 
restrict  my  assertion  to  the  minimum  possibile. 


IDEA  AND  ACTION 
E.  JORDAN 

SINCE  the  discovery  some  years  ago  of  the  importance  for 
psychology  of  the  reflex-arc  concept  there  has,  it  would  seem, 
been  instituted  a  general  propaganda  in  the  interest  of  apply 
ing  the  notion  to  the  methods  of  all  the  sciences  which  touch 
in  any  way  the  human  element.  Not  only  has  a  very  large 
part  of  the  output  of  the  psychological  laboratory  been 
committed  quite  exclusively  to  the  mechanism  involved  in 
the  concept,  but  recent  attempts  to  go  beyond  the  presup 
positions  of  experiment  merely,  in  the  direction  of  a  devel 
oped  psychological  theory,  also  seem  to  assume  that  all 
thought  on  matters  psychological  can  consist  only  in  de 
scriptions  of  the  way  consciousness  'behaves.'  And  be 
havior  as  thus  conceived  is  simply  the  sum  of  things  done 
by  consciousness  through  the  instrumentality  of  the  or 
ganism,  in  the  interest  of  results  achieved  in  the  immediate 
material  environment.  Even  the  most  refined  value-aspects 
of  ideas  and  feelings  are  but  fluttering  attempts  to  'do 
things,'  which  somehow  get  smothered  in  the  depths  of  the 
organism.  Consciousness  gets  up  in  the  morning,  stretches 
its  behavioristic  legs,  and  its  half-waking  awareness  of  things 
is  nothing  more  than  the  reverberation  through  the  'or 
ganism'  of  leg-stretching  movements  or  tendencies  to  move 
ment.  It  puts  on  its  behavioristic  clothes  by  hitching  itself 
up  to  previous  reflexes  somehow  left  vibrating  in  the  hy 
pothetical  organism;  it  recognizes  itself  as  the  same  'motor- 
complex'  that  went  to  bed  the  night  before  by  tendencies 
to  carry  through  the  same  motor  reactions  involved  in  lock 
ing  up  the  house,  which  reactions  still  synaptically  persist; 
its  decision  to  meet  the  day's  work  is  duly  'prefigured'  in 
muscular  effigiations,  and  it  goes  forth  to  conquer,  reflexly 
rejoicing  as  a  strong  man. 


246  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

Under  the  influence  of  the  further  assumption  that  all 
things  can  be  explained  psychologically,  the  same  attitude 
has  dominated  other  interests  than  those  of  scientific  psy 
chology.  In  economics  the  individual  is  now  an  economic 
force, — is,  in  fact,  merely  an  element  hopelessly  involved  in 
a  system  of  *  economic  forces.'  With  reference  to  produc 
tion  he  is  a  'cost'  or  a  'resource'  or  a  labor  'supply';  his 
existence  is  measured  in  'wants'  which  are  estimated  in 
terms  of  'prices'  in  distribution;  he  suffers  dissolution 
through  'consumption'  and  his  bones  are  gathered  to  his 
fathers  in  the  potter's  field  of  economic  waste.  Sociology 
makes  of  him  a  tissue  in  the  social  organism  (or  'organiza 
tion,'  as  they  seem  to  prefer  to  say  now),  girds  up  his  loins 
with  social  forces,  fulfills  his  destiny  in  social  instincts,  turns 
him  over  to  the  social  reformers,  who  mark  him  off  a  lot 
in  the  New  Jerusalem  of  socialized  conditions. 

To  put  the  case  briefly,  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  hu 
man  sciences  of  the  present,  the  human  individual  dissolves 
into  a  calculable  sum  of  physical,  biological,  and  psycho 
logical  'conditions.'  It  will  be  contended  in  this  paper 
that  this  point  of  view  originates  in  a  psychology  which  has 
wrongfully  appropriated  the  name  of  empirical  or  experi 
mental  and  in  a  psychologized  philosophy  which  has  adopted 
a  naive,  realistic  materialism  falsely  supposed  to  rest  on  the 
principles  of  scientific  method,  and  that  its  basis  is  to  be 
found  in  the  dogma  that  the  essence  of  the  idea  is  action. 

The  principle  that  every  mental  process  or  state  of  mind 
or  idea  (it  makes  no  difference  for  our  purposes  what  name 
is  given  it)  tends  to  express  itself  either  mediately  or  imme 
diately  through  movement  in  the  organism  is,  perhaps,  well 
founded.  But  that  this  tendency  to  expression  explains  any 
thing  more  than  certain  elementary  structural  characters  of 
the  idea  may  very  well  be  questioned.  The  case  is  quite 
clear  with  the  ordinary  ideas  or  mental  contents  which 
accompany  the  simple  necessities  of  action  involved  in  daily 
life.  As  I  go  through  the  daily  round  of  duties,  my  conduct 
is  adequately  described  as  a  complex  series  of  sense  images 
together  with  series  of  muscular  movements  more  or  less 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  247 

appropriate  thereto.  Here  we  are  on  the  simple  plane  of 
reflex  or  sensori-motor  reaction,  and  the  quality  of  the 
sensation  constitutes  perhaps  all  the  '  consciousness '  I 
have,  certainly  all  I  need  in  this  action-context.  The  same 
mechanism  disposes  of  the  entire  life  of  habit,  so  long,  at 
least,  as  habit  flows  on  undisturbed.  Similarly,  the  sensory 
reports  from  deep-lying,  organic  functions  touch  the  key 
for  the  discharge  of  movements  in  instinct,  so  that  the  entire 
life  as  organic  may  be  described  as  nervous  and  muscular 
automatism.  And  in  so  far  as  we  are  content  to  assume  that 
the  entire  content  of  'mind'  is  disposed  of  on  the  principle 
of  organic  automatism,  the  basis  of  our  psychology,  and  of 
the  philosophy  that  depends  upon  it,  is  simple  and  very  at 
tractive.  But  may  it  not  be  too  simple?  It  seems  that  our 
employment  of  this  assumption  would  necessarily  commit 
us  to  the  further  assumption  that  the  age-long  metaphysical 
problem  of  the  relation  of  mind  and  body  has  been  solved, 
and  that  an  empirical  demonstration  of  the  solution  can  be 
given.  But  it  is  just  in  this  assumption  that  the  difficulty 
lies.  That  is,  the  validity  of  the  assumption  rests  upon 
the  reality  of  the  problem,  which  ought  to  be  avoided  if  the 
principles  of  the  philosophy  of  action  are  to  be  consistently 
followed.  A  problem  set  for  us  in  immediate,  empirical  fact 
is  dodged  by  uncritically  accepting  the  identity  of  its  two 
terms.  In  the  face  of  the  facts  and  of  their  concreteness  and 
disparateness,  we  assume  that  mind  is  essentially  nothing 
but  functionings  in  the  organism. 

The  question  takes  on  sharp  outlines  when  we  employ 
actionist  presuppositions  in  the  description  of  certain  types 
of  mental  facts.  It  can,  of  course,  be  objected  that  descrip 
tion  does  not  require  any  presuppositions,  and  the  objection 
is  valid,  if  and  after  we  have  accepted  the  attitude  that 
presuppositions  (that  is,  ideas  which  are  not  immediately 
identifiable  with  organic  response)  are  not  involved  in  the 
mental  life  at  all,  but  that  that  life  is  merely  organic.  But 
even  a  superficial  examination  of  the  images  involved  in 
perception  and  memory  will  set  out  in  clear  contrast  to  each 
other  two  characters,  both  of  which  seem  to  be  root-elements 


248  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

of  the  image.  If  Bergson  has  meant  anything  in  the  discus 
sion  of  current  psychological  problems,  it  certainly  is  that 
mental  facts  are  not  as  simple  as  they  have  seemed.  On  this 
point  Bergson  has  been  led  to  adopt  a  position  that  might 
be  characterized  as  radically  empirical,  in  spite  of  the  fact 
that  the  rationalism  inherent  in  his  modes  of  thought  spoils 
much  of  his  discussion  by  trying  to  join  together  what  God 
hath  put  asunder.  Note  for  a  moment  his  handling  of  the 
facts  of  perception.  In  the  experience  of  immediate  fact  the 
unique  factor  is  that  an  object  offers  a  clue  to  the  organism 
upon  which  the  latter  is  to  react  in  some  way  advantageous 
to  itself.  Presented  fact  is  either  useful  or  not,  and  the  gist 
of  perception  is  disclosed  in  the  choice  which  the  body  makes 
among  prefigured  modes  of  reaction;  the  reaction  not  chosen 
degenerates  in  the  situation  in  a  way  which  renders  it  merely 
'virtual.'  This  virtual  action  is  the  pure  perception  and  is 
distinguished  from  actual  perception  by  the  fact  that  the 
latter  passes  off  reflexly  through  the  organism.  Because  the 
latter  is  immediately  accounted  for  in  terms  of  organic  re 
sponse,  no  consciousness  in  the  strict  sense  is  involved,  and 
we  have  merely  the  case  of  automatic  adaptation  between 
one  'real  image'  and  another,  the  unique  element  being 
simply  the  fact  that  one  of  the  images  is  privileged.  But  in 
case  the  adaptation  does  not  take  place  in  this  immediate 
and  automatic  fashion,  when  there  is  a  hitch  between  stimu 
lus  and  response,  the  action  originally  meant  by  the  stimu 
lus,  that  is,  the  real  content  of  the  object  presented  as  this 
meaning,  is  seen  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  real  situation 
to  become  precipitated  or  'prefigured'  as  virtual  action. 
It  is  then,  it  would  seem,  act  as  viewed  from  the  side  of  its 
representative  or  cognitive  function,  the  idea  of  the  logicians. 
Thus  the  attempt  to  force  the  duplicity  of  fact  into  the 
simple  form  of  an  outward  act,  regarded  as  homogeneous 
throughout,  defeats  its  own  end  by  showing  clearly  the  con 
trary  fact,  that  the  image  invariably  presents  two  faces,  the 
one  being  the  motor  tendency  to  reproduce  its  object,  the 
other  the  representative  function  of  intending  or  meaning 
its  object.  And  Bergson's  laborious  analysis  makes  it  fairly 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  249 

evident  that  the  image  can  never  be  so  simple  as  not  to 
consist  of  both.  Further,  his  method  of  reaching  simplicity 
here  is  significant,  and  possibly  illustrates  all  methods  hav 
ing  similar  purposes,  that  is,  one  of  the  aspects  of  the  image 
is  found  to  be  merely  *  theoretical.'  But  this  looks  like 
neglecting  a  fact  because  it  does  not  behave  as  theory  re 
quires. 

Clearly,  then,  although  the  assumption  is  that  action  is 
the  only  element  involved  in  any  real  situation,  that  same 
element  seems  to  split  itself  into  two  very  different  parts, 
the  one  being  the  action  as  a  fluent  and  living  relation  be 
tween  real  things, — an  act  which  occurs  and  in  occurring 
actually  creates, — the  other  fulfilling  its  function  by  merely 
*  meaning'  an  action  which  is  deferred.  But  being  deferred 
means  that  it  does  not  occur,  and  failing  to  occur  means 
that  it  does  not  express  itself  through  the  organism.  Thus 
the  crux  of  the  matter  for  a  psychologized  logic  is  just  the 
fact  that  the  break  between  the  neural  or  physical  conditions 
on  the  one  side,  and  the  act  which  is  to  modify  that  set  of 
conditions  on  the  other,  is  the  slip  betwixt  the  cup  and  the 
lip.  And  while  most  idealistic  schemes  have  thinly  covered 
the  breach  with  assumptions,  and  have  beclouded  it  with 
fine-spun  logical  trivialities,  the  best  that  modern  actionists 
seem  able  to  do  is  to  bridge  the  gap  with  a  hypothetical  con 
tact  mystified  under  the  name  of  synapse,  thus  trading  one 
mystery  for  another.  For  the  synapse  is  now  a  physical  or 
neural  connection,  now  a  poetic  or  energic  'as  if.'  It  is  as  if 
two  liquids  were  separated  by  a  membrane  of  rather  high 
degree  of  impermeability.  And  the  result  is  that  continuity 
of  action  between  the  organism  and  its  environment,  which 
was  established  in  the  first  place  by  assumption,  now  re 
quires  a  second  supposition, — and  one  of  rather  doubtful 
probability, — to  render  its  position  secure.  But  when  we 
have  to  bolster  up  one  presupposition  by  another,  by  what 
compulsion  are  we  obliged  to  stop  with  two?  It  would  be 
far  simpler  to  take  the  common  sense  view  that  an  act  is  an 
indivisible  unity,  which,  as  unity,  can  have  whatever  func 
tions  or  characters  it  has  in  fact,  and  that  it  requires  none 


250  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

of  the  ingenuity  of  psychological  atomism  to  ' establish' 
its  simplicity.  Bergson's  purpose  seems  to  be  to  show  that 
the  depths  of  ontology,  which  are  included,  of  course,  within 
the  profundities  of  epistemology,  are  fathomed  when  knowl 
edge  of  the  act  leads  us  to  the  vision  of  duration  and  futurity. 
But  it  is  just  this  vision  that  many  of  us  do  not  survive. 
And  yet  "how  goodly  had  the  vision  been."  For,  when  ac 
tion  is  thus  caught  on  the  wing,  it  vouches  for  its  existence  in 
another  form,  viz.,  that  in  which  it  does  not  act,  but  simply 
represents.  While  the  latter  as  pure  perception  exists  only 
theoretically,  its  import  becomes  significant  as  a  troublesome 
negative  limitation  to  the  out-reaching  ambition  of  the  form 
which  exists  practically.  That  is,  its  theoretic  persistence 
posits  the  whole  field  of  reality  as  cognitive  and  interpreta 
tive,  and  as  not  requiring  in  any  sense  the  urgencies  of  me 
chanistic  energies  as  a  final  guarantee  of  its  right  to  reality. 
And  this  means  that  a  static  world  of  representation  is, 
after  all,  behind  Bergson's  attempt  to  create  a  world  of  pure 
functional  reals.  The  same  dualism  of  psychological  reals 
persists  throughout  Bergson's  work,  and  the  problems  it 
presents  give  him  occasion  for  most  of  the  significant  insights 
which  that  work  offers  for  modern  thought.  We  have  seen 
that  perception  is,  on  the  one  side,  pure  act  as  prevenience, 
and,  on  the  other,  act  as  carried  through  to  response.  Mem 
ory  shows  the  two  forms  as  pure  memory  and  habit-memory. 
And  although  the  pure  forms  are  'only  theoretical,'  yet  it  is 
apparent  that  his  thought  would  not  hold  together  for  a 
moment,  if  they  were  not  given  equal  status  with  the  prac 
tical  forms  of  experience.  It  seems  clear  that  not  every 
aspect  of  experience  is  necessarily  included  in  the  notion  of 
action. 

If  we  should  consider  the  most  potent  factors  in  the 
thought  of  the  present,  it  would  become  more  and  more 
evident  that  the  emphasis  is  in  every  field  upon  the  dynamic 
and  living,  rather  than  upon  the  eternal  verities  of  an  older 
type  of  thought.  And  by  dynamic  and  living  we  do  not 
mean  the  spiritual  impulsions  of  a  life  assumed  to  be  made 
up  essentially  of  comfortable  accomplishments  and  close- 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  251 

fitting  realizations,  but  rather  the  ruder  and  cruder  life 
which  embodies  insatiable  urgencies  arising  from  the  neces 
sities  imposed  upon  the  organism  by  a  world  of  like  structure. 
The  home  of  the  spirit  is  to  be  found  and  founded  in  the 
flesh,  and  the  life  of  the  spirit  is  to  be  saved  to  the  flesh. 
Philosophy  glories  in  the  fact  that  it  is  of  the  earth  earthy. 
It  may  be  worth  while  to  note  some  of  the  many  directions 
in  which  this  motive  is  finding  expression.  And  first,  re 
membering  that  the  spirit  of  the  modern  age  is  scientific 
and  positivist,  one  would  naturally  expect  that  science  would 
show  the  first  and  fundamental  postulate  of  the  modern 
mind  in  the  principle  that  matter  is  to  be  defined  in  terms 
of  energy.  The  old  atom  of  homogeneous  stuff  is  displaced 
by  the  new  center  of  forces,  and  the  latter  receives  definition 
in  terms  of  mathematical  relations,  which,  in  their  turn, 
seem  to  be  exchanging  their  old-fashioned  stability  and 
'universality'  for  functional  relations  to  their  'conditions,' 
which  conditions  are,  once  more,  functional  intersections  of 
other  dynamic  lines  of  force.  Logic  follows  suit  by  regarding 
the  hypothetical  judgment,  once  conceived,  perhaps,  as 
foundation  and  superstructure,  as  representative  of  a  course 
of  evolutional  progress,  and  the  fact  that  little  seems  to 
have  been  accomplished  in  the  way  of  developing  the  con 
ception  may  merely  argue  the  truth  of  the  generally  accepted 
dogma  that  logic  must  await  the  realization  of  definiteness 
in  scientific  method.  And  just  now  the  scientific  method 
seems  fairly  to  wallow  in  insurgent  fluidity  with  its  conse 
quent  indefiniteness.  Action,  movement,  change, — these 
are  the  categories  that  are  fundamental  everywhere. 

But  the  interest  in  change  is  temporal  and  practical  and 
human.  It  is,  then,  in  the  fields  of  the  practical  interests 
that  we  may  expect  to  find  the  most  interesting  attempts  to 
apply  the  principles  of  actionist  philosophy;  at  least,  it  is 
for  those  interests  that  most  of  our  philosophers  show  special 
concern.  It  might  seem  a  rather  precarious  procedure  to 
undertake  to  incorporate  the  uncertainties  of  changing  fact 
into  the  instrument  whose  function  it  is  to  find  definiteness 
(however  low  a  degree)  in  the  very  inwardness  of  the  facts 


252  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

themselves.  And  yet  that  seems  to  be  what  is  attempted, 
and  results  so  far  do  not  look  reassuring.  That  is,  a  logic  of 
change  has  perhaps  not  yet  been  worked  out, — the  *  logic  of 
evolution'  to  the  contrary  notwithstanding, — and  it  may 
be  that  the  very  notion  of  ordered  knowledge  within  an  ex 
perience  of  fluent  fact  is  what  Hobbes  called  a  'metaphorical 
speech.'  If  one  accepts  a  philosophy  or  logic  of  change, 
one  is  committed  to  the  acceptance  also  of  a  world  which 
consists  of  other  things  than  facts,  a  world  in  which  anything 
becoming  another  thing  is  a  serious  problem.  For  under  this 
condition  the  idea  as  act  becomes  a  cause  which  may  upset 
the  world  of  fact  at  any  point  or  at  any  moment.  The  act 
becomes  free,  its  effects  unpredictable,  thus  contravening  the 
very  scientific  method  which  called  it  into  being.  And  this 
difficulty  is  only  avoided  by  reflecting  that,  while  an  act 
of  creative  power,  the  idea  is  also  a  represented  value. 

The  philosophy  whose  theoretical  form  we  are  here  at 
tempting  to  state  may  be  summarized  thus.  The  idea  is 
an  act  and  nothing  else;  and  further,  the  act  which  is  the 
idea  is  the  action  or  movement  involved  in  the  functioning 
of  the  organism.  Then  every  situation  which  has  hitherto 
been  erroneously  supposed  one  in  which  we  should  think 
ourselves  straight  and  then  'give  the  thought  his  act'  is 
really  a  situation  in  which  an  act  of  ours  is  included  as  an 
element  in  a  larger  functional  whole,  this  inclusion  being 
the  essence  of  consciousness  and  the  process  of  thought. 
Yet  thought  may,  after  the  act  is  completed,  dwell  on  the 
question  whether  the  act  was  successful  with  reference  to 
other  possible  acts,  possible  acts  having  reference  to  alter 
natives  of  action  distinguishable  in  the  situation  as  a  whole. 
That  is,  consciousness  is  reflexive  rather  than  reflective. 
Thought  is  then  co-terminous  with  the  physical  and  physio 
logical  processes  of  movement,  these  processes  being  charged 
with  the  further  capacity  for  post  mortem  examination  of 
the  relations  between  the  situation  which  they  constitute 
and  other  situations  of  the  same  sort.  Life  is  action;  thought 
or  consciousness  is  useful,  that  is,  real,  in  so  far  as  it  renders 
action  successful;  that  is,  it  is  successful  action.  Successful 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  253 

action  is  that  which  issues  in  proper  conditions  of  further 
action.  But  action  may  embody  and  fulfill  the  finer  needs 
(avoiding  the  term  purposes)  of  the  aesthetic  and  religious 
experience,  as  well  as  the  coarser  and  commoner  needs  of 
the  organism. 

There  is  much  that  is  satisfying  and  attractive  about  such 
a  scheme,  and  most  persons  will  find  little  difficulty  in  ac 
cepting  it, — so  far  as  it  goes  and  with  the  proper  restrictions 
and  limitations.  And  if  belief  in  idealism  (for  which  the 
above  is  supposed  to  be  an  antidote)  ever  involved  the  con 
ception  of  the  life-process  as  a  complacent  contemplation 
of  consummate  truth,  then  idealists  should  ask  pardon  for 
their  sins.  There  are,  however,  two  parts  to  this  creed,  and 
these  will  not  permit  of  being  confused  without  serious  con 
sequences.  Nor  will  they  permit  of  over-emphasis  on  either 
part  without  destroying  the  balance  of  forces  which  repre 
sents  the  truth  of  the  creed.  The  two  clauses  are  that  life 
is  action,  either  as  (i)  the  act  of  critical  estimation  or  evalua 
tion,  as  for  example  in  aesthetic  or  logical  experience,  or  as 
(2)  the  act  of  the  organism  in  accomplishing  results  which 
condition  its  further  action,  that  is,  results  in  what  are  or 
dinarily  called  material  things. 

An  emphasis  upon  either  of  these  two  tenets  which  carries 
with  it  neglect  of  the  other  is  fatal  to  any  well-ordered  social 
or  individual  life,  and  as  a  social  order  of  individual  lives  is 
the  highest  of  conceivable  human  ends,  undue  emphasis  in 
either  direction  entails  a  misunderstanding  of  human  motives 
and  a  confusion  of  the  meaning  of  the  term  practical.  As  a 
case  of  overworking  the  first  of  the  principles  might  be  named 
any  of  the  ancient  or  modern  logical  idealisms  which  stand 
out  so  attractively  in  the  history  of  philosophy.  As  poetic 
schemes  of  pure  values  known  in  placid  contemplation,  they 
issue  in  the  ideal  of  a  timeless,  universal  Garden  of  Eden, 
such  as  appears  again  and  again  from  Plato's  Republic  to 
Wells's  New  Worlds  for  Old.  These  have  been  real  in  so  far 
as  they  have  stimulated  men's  minds  to  try  to  work  them 
out  in  the  flesh.  But  their  notorious  falsity  'on  the  whole' 
is  well  exemplified  in  the  actual  history  of  the  New  Jeru- 


254  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

salem,  the  supposed  'reality'  of  which  has  drugged  with 
overdoses  of  'hope  and  trust'  the  spirit  that  should  have 
accomplished  a  good  human  state,  expecting  thus  to  conquer 
by  waiting  and  through  inaction  deferring  to  the  timeless  a 
human  ideal  which  should  have  been  operative  here  and 
now.  There  has  been  further  confusion  by  compounding  this 
idealistic  view  with  scientific  atomism,  in  the  hope  of  saving 
the  individual  from  the  melee  occasioned  by  the  attempt  to 
get  things  together  iiberhaupt.  An  idealism  saved  over  from 
the  period  of  mediaeval  universalism  runs  hopelessly  together 
with  modern  scientific  atomism,  and  the  result  is  the  absurd 
confusion  of  economic  individualism  in  practical  affairs  and 
the  hopeless  effort  to  identify  the  individual  with  the  uni 
versal  by  sheer  force  of  logic.  And  when  the  outcome  of  the 
attempt  is  accepted  as  a  principle  of  philosophy,  any  and 
all  morality  seems  to  be  rendered  impracticable  thereby. 

But  if,  on  a  basis  of  the  philosophy  of  the  pure  thought- 
act,  we  come  to  grief  in  mere  contemplative  appreciation, 
the  issues  of  the  opposite  point  of  view  are  worse.  Action 
being  accepted  as  the  basis  of  the  reality  of  life,  emphasis 
comes  to  be  laid  on  the  mere  gaining  of  results,  without 
taking  the  trouble  to  inquire  whether  our  results  are  of  any 
consequence.  Indeed,  the  only  criterion  imposed  by  our 
actionist  principle  upon  any  result  is  that  it  serve  as  a  con 
dition  for  further  results,  which  in  turn  are  judged  by  the 
same  standard.  Hence  the  apotheosis  of  'process'  and 
'tendency'  in  theoretical  affairs,  and  the  Mammonism  of 
'getting  things  done'  in  practice.  The  weaknesses  of  the 
philosophy  of  evolution  and  the  indefiniteness  of  its  cate 
gories  probably  find  their  roots  here.  A  full  discussion  of 
these  weaknesses  would  sooner  or  later  implicate  the  prin 
ciples  and  practices  of  scientific  method  itself,  but  that  lies 
outside  our  present  purpose.  On  the  other  hand,  a  scheme 
which  looks  for  justification  to  practical  consequences  should 
welcome  an  analysis  of  some  of  the  interests  within  which 
practical  consequences  are  the  desideratum.  Let  us  there 
fore  look  at  some  of  the  current  motives  involved  in  our 
more  important  practical  disciplines,  with  a  view  to  seeing 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  255 

their  relations  to  the  prevailing  direction  of  present-day 
thought,  thus  briefly  suggesting  what  the  application  of  ac- 
tionist  philosophy  to  the  interests  of  education,  politics,  and 
ethics  brings  forth  as  its  more  weighty  practical  conse 
quences.  Even  at  the  risk  of  overstepping  the  bounds  of 
philosophy,  we  may  attempt  to  disclose  the  *  business'  mo 
tives  which  actionist  principles  seem  to  make  dominant 
everywhere.  One  begins  to  suspect  that  the  degree  to  which 
*  practical'  interests  dominate  the  present  social  and  political 
situation  constitutes  the  reductio  ad  absurdum  of  the  phi 
losophy  of  action. 

A  superficial  glance  at  current  educational  tendencies  is 
perhaps  conducive  to  hopefulness.  Many  movements  seem 
to  be  indicative  of  an  approaching  democracy  hitherto  not 
conceivable.  We  hear  proclaimed  in  nearly  every  educa 
tional  address  the  principles  of  democratic  or  universal 
education  laid  down  in  the  governmental  schemes  estab 
lished  by  our  fathers.  Educational  journals  are  filled  with 
the  same  sentiment.  The  interest  in  education  is  declared 
to  be  wide  and  popular.  There  was  never  a  time  when  well- 
trained  persons  were  in  such  demand.  Even  business  is 
supposed  to  require  persons  of  largeness  of  mind  and  round 
ness  of  character.  The  i people'  are  clamorous  for  educa 
tion.  And  if  our  notions  of  education  were  determined  by 
current  discussion,  we  would  be  obliged  to  conclude  that 
the  American  people  have  risen  as  one  man  and  declared 
that  education  is  the  panacea  for  all  the  ills  of  life.  No  doubt 
there  is  a  fundamental  faith  in  education,  even  a  belief  that 
it  constitutes  for  us  an  only  hope;  but  there  is  no  correspond 
ing  degree  of  intelligence  in  our  attempts  to  understand  what 
the  process  means.  And  in  our  zeal  for  education  we  are 
ready  to  'do'  anything  except  to  try  to  think  clearly. 
Many  things  are  done  already,  so  many,  it  may  be,  that  a 
generation  of  clear-headedness  will  have  to  pass  before  we 
shall  see  that  many  of  the  same  things  will  require  to  be 
undone.  Briefly,  the  notion  of  what  is  involved  in  education 
as  a  process  and  as  an  accomplishment  has  recently  changed; 
but  it  seems  never  to  have  occurred  to  our  experts  that  the 


256  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

change  may  be  for  the  worse.  Since  the  initiation  of  the 
elective  system  there  has  steadily  been  growing  up  the  con 
viction  that  anything  which  may  happen  to  interest  the  in 
dividual  provides  satisfactory  matter  for  the  educational 
process.  But  a  little  critical  analysis  of  this  principle  would 
have  shown  that  it  rests  upon  a  questionable  sensationalistic 
or  rather  impressionistic  psychology,  and  further,  that  it 
implies  that  the  standard  for  education  rests  upon  the  ca 
price  of  the  person  to  be  educated,  rather  than  upon  the 
judgment  of  the  person  who  is  educated.  It  is  he  that  is 
sick  that  is  to  be  the  physician.  In  practice,  therefore,  since 
the  child  is  fundamentally  active  rather  than  thoughtful, 
his  interest  demands  that  the  process  be  adapted  to  things 
he  can  do.  Consequently  the  curriculum  must  be  made  over, 
first,  in  the  interest  of  laboratory  science  at  the  expense  of 
languages  and  the  so-called  cultural  subjects,  and  secondly, 
in  the  interests  of  the  ' practical'  at  the  expense  of  the 
knowledge-aspects  of  the  sciences.  First  Latin,  Greek,  etc., 
had  to  give  way  to  physics,  chemistry,  etc.;  and  as  for  the 
rest,  the  sciences  themselves  soon  were  superseded  by  voca 
tional  subjects;  now  we  have  ' shop-work.'  A  list  of  the 
'practical5  subjects  now  occupying  a  place  in  the  curriculum 
is  enough  to  fill  with  dismay  and  despair  the  mind  of  any  one 
not  committed  entirely  to  commercialized  materialism.  It 
can  be  confidently  asserted  that  a  large  majority  of  those 
engaged  in  the  actual  work  of  teaching  are  skeptical  of  the 
results  obtainable  in  these  subjects.  And  while  it  is  sincerely 
hoped  that  sooner  or  later  serious  permanent  results  may  be 
obtained  from  these  interests,  the  intelligence  required  to 
direct  them  to  that  end  does  not  now  exist  in  the  minds 
either  of  the  experts  or  of  the  business  men  who  (actionists 
all)  are  jointly  responsible  for  their  incorporation  in  the 
school  system.  But  things  are  done  nevertheless;  also  pell- 
mell.  From  the  point  of  view  of  the  philosophy  of  action 
the  situation  begins  to  look  like  this:  Practical  men,  dis 
cerning  that  the  older  education  based  on  ideas  and  com 
mitted  to  the  belief  that  significant  results  must  involve 
ideas,  see  that  results  in  this  form  are  not  immediately 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  257 

practical,  not  convertible  into  cash.  They  cannot  be  con 
verted  into  things  of  value, — value  meaning  what  can  be 
represented  by  economic  activity.  For  them,  to  learn  is  to 
do;  to  do  is  to  make;  to  make  is  to  produce  the  conditions  of 
further  action;  in  short,  the  educative  process  is  the  com 
mercial  process.  To  prove  the  point  our  experts  commit 
the  fallacy  of  converting,  "The  commercial  process  is  educa 
tive,"  into  "The  educative  process  is  commercial." 

A  similar  arraignment  must  be  made  of  practical  politics. 
It  would  perhaps  be  contrary  to  every  American  tradition 
to  ask  that  a  legislator  be  prepared  with  ideas,  or  that  he 
should  defend  his  action  by  appealing  to  ideas.  The  only 
requirement  is  that  he  get  results,  these  being  usually  in  the 
form  of  'pork'  or  of  a  shave  in  the  tax-rate.  The  latter 
result  may  be  obtained  (however  unjustly)  by  shifting  the 
burden  from  the  constituency  to  the  shoulders  of  a  section 
or  class  unable  to  defend  itself  by  reason  of  numerical  or 
commercial  weakness  or  of  ignorance.  No  questions  of  the 
right  constitution  of  the  social  order  seem  to  be  worthy  of 
consideration,  but  each  problem  that  arises  must  be  settled 
with  reference  only  to  immediate  material  results.  Aside 
from  the  possibility  of  dollars  and  cents  to  be  made  either 
for  the  legislator  or  for  the  constituency,  the  next  and  per 
haps  most  important  consideration  is  the  influence  of  a  vote 
on  the  likelihood  of  re-election.  Again,  the  ideal  is  to  do 
things,  or  to  get  or  have  things  done.  That  considerations 
of  a  purely  speculative  or,  so  far  as  immediate  consequences 
go,  impractical  character  might  contribute  after  all  to  the 
accomplishment  of  results  more  satisfactory,  even  from  the 
material  point  of  view,  than  mere  dependence  upon  methods 
and  processes,  is  a  principle  whose  statement  will  evoke  only 
merriment  from  our  practical  men  of  affairs.  Once  more 
the  emphasis  is  placed  upon  action  to  the  utter  neglect  of 
ideas  or  principles.  Thought  is  necessary;  yes,  but  only  to 
distinguish  methods,  never  ends.  Thinking  is  doing,  or 
perhaps  better,  getting  things  done. 

It  is,  however,  in  the  interest  of  morality  that  this  criticism 
of  actionist  principles  is  undertaken.  Under  these  principles 


258  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  conscious  life  is  identified  with,  or  involved  in,  the  com 
plex  of  physical  or  physiological  conditions  which  constitute 
a  situation  of  fact.  Ethics  is  then  a  purely  descriptive 
science,  hypothesis  itself  being  a  descriptive  process;  all  ques 
tions  are  questions  of  fact.  Morality  is  that  life  which 
knows,  or  rather  senses,  or  perhaps  better  still,  tends  to 
reproduce,  its  relations  to  its  evolutional  conditions,  its 
mores.  The  mores  are  a  set  of  conditions  which  determine 
both  the  processes  and  the  results  of  present  action.  Causa 
tion  is  the  moral  law.  Whatever  is,  is  right;  morality  is 
custom,  and  "It  is  being  done"  is  the  last  word.  Yet  this 
scheme  of  activity  is  offered  as  a  substitute  for  older  idealistic 
schemes  on  the  ground  that  the  latter  furnish  no  room  for 
spontaneity;  that  the  life  of  humanity  is  tied  up  hard  and 
fast  in  a  system  perfected  from  the  beginning.  The  older 
views  can  offer,  it  is  asserted,  nothing  as  possible  in  new 
and  significant  and  creative  activity  which  was  not  contained 
already  in  a  world  bound  tight  by  systems  of  immutable  law. 
There  can  happen  nothing  which  was  not  implied  in  reality 
from  everlasting  to  everlasting.  When  something  occurs,  it 
is  but  a  rendering  explicit  what  already  incorrigibly  and 
completely  was  implicit  and  given.  And  much  fine  sport 
has  accrued  from  the  sorry  predicament  of  something  which 
'is'  but  still  is  not  ' given.'  But  an  act  described  as  implied 
in  the  complex  of  ideas  which  make  up  the  character  of  a 
conscious  individual  is  no  more  predetermined  than  the  same 
act  described  as  a  tendency  in  hypothetical  nervous  con 
nections  in  the  organism,  or  as  tendencies  in  the  social  group. 
That  the  idealistic  language  refers  to  fact  immediately  open 
to  common  sense  is  evident  by  the  moral  response  (we  are 
appealing  to  the  actionist's  principle  of  significant  action) 
which  it  elicits  from  a  very  wide  diversity  of  persons  to  whom 
the  mere  scientific  argument  will  mean  nothing.  In  other 
words,  that  a  given  course  of  action  is  the  normal  outcome 
of  the  presence  of  a  given  set  of  ideas  probably  means  more 
(in  terms  of  behavior  even)  than  to  say  that  the  course  of 
action  had  its  conditions  in  mores  or  causes  apostrophically 
described  as  tendencies  to  act.  But  the  actionist  or  be- 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  259 

haviorist  will  probably  insist  that  he  has  never  meant  what 
is  here  attributed  to  him.    Then  what  has  he  meant? 

After  all,  from  the  moral  point  of  view,  what  is  the  differ 
ence  whether  you  conceive  your  world  as  fixed  and  transfixed 
by  relations  which  hold  together  systems  of  ideas,  or  as 
bound  up  and  determined  by  natural  laws  which  knit  to 
gether  complexes  of  facts  and  tendencies  to  movement  ?  As 
a  criticism  of  the  idealism  which  gets  lost  in  a  maze  of  con- 
tactless  relations,  the  call  for  a  return  to  facts  is  a  propos; 
but  when  facts  have  no  meaning  except  what  they  can  sur 
reptitiously  obtain  from  fictions,  one  begins  strongly  to  sus 
pect  that  the  criticism  is  merely  negative  and  skeptical. 
Likewise  it  may  not  be  altogether  out  of  place  to  suggest  that 
the  skeptical  critic  is  either  consciously  or  unconsciously 
replacing  his  own  ideas  with  hypothetical  entities,  such  as, 
for  example,  the  potential  energy  of  the  physicist.  In  any 
case,  a  'fact'  is  as  easily  represented  by  the  idea  of  relation 
as  by  a  tendency  to  movement;  it  is  as  simple  to  explain 
potential  energy,  considered  as  the  fact  that  certain  conse 
quences  will  result  when  certain  conditions  are  fulfilled,  by 
referring  the  situation  to  the  purpose  which  may  reach  the 
consequence  through  fulfilling  the  conditions,  as  by  describ 
ing  the  consequences  and  conditions  after  the  event  has  oc 
curred.  And  apart  from  considerations  of  simplicity,  the 
demand  that  the  ideas  be  made  functions  in  real  situations 
is  met  already  when  we  assume  purposes  as  elementary  to 
the  situations,  whereas  the  'epistemological'  difficulties  so 
much  flouted  of  late  have  to  be  met  only  when  we  begin 
with  the  'facts,'  which  we  tend  to  regard  as  independent 
ultimates.  There  seems  to  be,  then,  logically,  no  advantage 
which  either  of  these  points  of  view  can  claim  over  the  other; 
one  justifies  itself  by  reference  to  certain  typical  characters 
of  experience,  the  other  by  reference  to  other  characters;  and 
each  type  seems  as  'real'  as  the  other. 

To  cover  this  logical  impasse  the  philosophers  of  action 
take  refuge  in  the  practical,  in  much  the  same  way  and  per 
haps  for  the  same  reason  that  some,  possibly  all,  types  of 
idealism  resort  to  the  contemplative.  The  practical  means, 


260  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

so  far  as  any  statement  yet  produced  is  concerned,  the  at 
tainment  of  results  through  action  of  the  type  which  is  to  be 
found  in  "the  concrete,  living  experience  of  every-day  life." 
Thought-action  involved  in  scientific  research  is  of  this  type; 
in  fact,  all  processes  of  thought  or  experience  are  funda 
mentally  identical  in  this  form,  in  so  far  at  least  as  they  can 
attain  to  this  form.  The  only  theoretical  considerations 
which  seem  to  be  necessary  are  involved  in  seeing  merely 
that  a  given  process  is  true  to  type,  that  it  conforms  to  the 
condition-activity-result  standard.  Conformity  of  a  given 
process  or  fact  with  this  standard  is  truth.  Failure  to  con 
form  is  falsity,  but  is  yet  fact,  so  error  is  real.  Thought  is 
practical,  or  better,  is  practice,  action.  Its  interest  is  not 
in  results  as  ends,  for  results  are  of  consequence  only  as 
conditions  of  further  action.  Reality  is  the  complex  within 
which  the  common  factor  is  the  movement  of  thought  (and 
this  is  organic  with  physiological  movement)  or  what  may 
become  thought, — the  apotheosis  of  process. 

It  will  be  readily  admitted,  I  think,  that  such  a  scheme 
corresponds  closely  to  the  facts  of  actual  life.  The  '  thought' 
process  here  described  is  a  fairly  faithful  account  of  what 
actually  takes  place  in  the  world,  of  what  actually  is  done. 
It  has  probably  represented  the  dominant  human  attitude 
of  the  past  century,  perhaps  also  of  the  preceding  century. 
It  is  certainly  the  attitude  of  scientific  interests  throughout 
the  entire  modern  period,  and  the  tremendous  advances  in 
natural  science  are  due  to  it.  The  accomplishments  of  man 
in  political  history  are  results  of  a  method  of  thought  or  an 
attitude  which  could  be  properly  described  in  the  same  way. 
The  English  political  method  being  taken  as  typical  (and  we 
must  remember  that  it  is  perhaps  to  the  English  that  the 
greatest  advances  in  scientific  thought  are  due),  that  method 
has  consisted  in  the  reference  of  present  action  to  past  results 
in  the  interest  of  new  results  of  the  same  kind, — precedent. 
The  development  of  America  materially  and  politically  has 
followed  the  same  course,  in  spite  of  some  idealism  which,  in 
an  unguarded  moment  of  enthusiasm,  crept  into  the  original 
governmental  scheme.  There  is  no  end  of  the  illustrative 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  261 

proofs  which  might  be  adduced  to  show  that  the  method  of 
human  success  is  trial  and  error. 

But  what  has  been  the  total  result?  Have  we  after  all, 
granting  that  philosophy  is  interested  in  life,  attained  to  a 
life  that  we  can  unreservedly  call  worthy  or  significant? 
Have  we  not,  if  we  look  at  the  matter  from  the  point  of  view 
of  actual  practice,  failed  to  reach  a  'life,'  in  the  sense  in 
which  every  person  demands  life,  but  have  succeeded  merely 
in  expressing  a  blind  will  to  succeed?  It  may  be  very 
strongly  suspected  that  in  the  enthusiasm  for  getting  things 
done  we  have  substituted  for  the  truth-values  and  appre 
ciation-values  that  make  up  the  content  of  life  a  system  of 
abstract  method-values  and  thing-values  which  furnish 
merely  the  conditions  of  living,  not  well,  but  anyhow.  And 
our  suggestion  made  above  that  a  wrong  emphasis  here  is 
fatal,  now  seems  to  convict  us  of  having  committed  ourselves 
to  a  life  of  material  or  economic  determinism,  in  which  the 
thought-life  is  a  mere  instrument  for  the  accomplishment 
of  external  results.  It  would  be  hardly  to  the  point  to  argue 
that  such  a  consequence  is  not  meant  by  explaining  thought 
in  terms  of  action,  or  to  insist  that  thought-action  is  re 
stricted  to  solving  real  problems  on  the  higher  planes  of  vital 
activity,  while  insisting  continually  that  philosophy  must 
keep  in  touch  with  actual  life.  In  this  case  actual  life  must 
be  the  test  of  our  thought-system,  and  the  life  that  we  find 
actual  is  one  which,  practically,  is  determined  by  principles 
unworthy  of  any  serious  effort  of  thought.  Nor  is  this  a 
merely  temporal  or  personal  pessimistic  judgment.  The 
present  industrial  system  with  its  methods  is  generally 
recognized  to  represent  the  life-scheme  of  practically  every 
individual,  whether  the  individual  is  aware  of  the  fact  or 
condemns  the  system  or  not.  And  this  system,  although  it 
fulfills  the  requirements  of  a  life  modelled  after  the  prin 
ciples  laid  down  by  a  philosophy  of  action,  stands  condemned 
as  unworthy  of  a  human  life  by  every  person  who  can  think 
at  all.  It  would  be  simple  to  explain  the  great  war  in  terms 
of  conditions  and  results  in  the  complex  of  life-action,  but 
can  the  life  that  is  wasted  be  explained  in  terms  of  war- 


262  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

action?  At  a  certain  point  explanation  must  become  justi 
fication;  and  it  is  hard  to  get  justification  out  of  a  mere  com 
plex  of  impersonal  situations.  It  is  admitted,  then,  that  our 
philosophy  must  be  based  upon  life.  But  a  reference  of 
philosophic  thought  to  actual  life,  without  any  consideration 
of  its  unrealized  possibilities,  only  condemns  the  mode  of 
life  and  the  philosophy  that  is  found  to  agree  with  it.  And 
a  continual  emphasis  on  the  practical  will  never  supply  the 
checks  necessary  to  keep  the  life-movement  on  the  upward 
trend.  What  has  perhaps  actually  happened  is  that  we  have 
been  so  drugged  by  continued  material  success  through  mere 
doing  that  we  have  at  last  attempted  to  accept  the  ethics  of 
modern  industry  as  a  principle  for  a  universal  philosophy; 
we  have  accepted  the  philosophy  of  a  life  for  a  philosophy 
of  life.  And  just  now,  in  the  welter  of  world  murder  and  in 
the  living  death  imposed  by  the  industrial  system,  life  is  pay 
ing  the  forfeit. 

No  doubt  a  new  philosophy  is  at  present  required.  But 
it  cannot  be  one  which  expresses  no  more  than  life  as  it  is, 
but  must  show  that  what  is,  contains  suggestions  of  new  di 
rections  of  worth.  And  things  of  worth  (except  economically) 
are  not  discovered  or  produced  through  action  alone,  but 
rather  through  emphasis  on  critical  reflection  after  action 
has  laid  down  the  bases  of  life.  It  is  only  upon  correction  of 
action  that  life  can  begin.  At  least,  corrective  reflection  is 
a  fair  substitute  for  that  bumptious  strenuosity  which  follows 
the  placing  of  emphasis  upon  action.  Maybe  we  shall  all 
be  willing  to  accept  the  philosophy  of  doing,  when  men  are 
thereby  shown  how  to  act  as  men  and  not  simply  as  instru 
ments  in  that  specific  unhuman  or  inhuman  situation  which 
happens  to  exist  and  to  catch  men's  fancy,  or  which  may 
artificially  and  in  the  interest  of  gross  material  results  be 
constructed  with  the  purpose  to  take  advantage  of  human 
weakness.  We  may  then  come  to  the  point  of  asserting  the 
truth  of  the  principle  that  thought  is  action.  But  there  are 
acts  and  acts.  And  the  qualitative  differences  between  acts 
make  all  the  real  differences  in  the  world,  although  they 
may  be  only  differences  in  degree.  That  thought  is  action 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  263 

does  not  entitle  us  to  say  without  qualification  that  action 
is  thought,  as  undoubtedly  is  the  tendency  in  discussions  of 
the  practical.  The  production  of  material  results  through 
organic  response,  or  the  resolution  of  unsatisfactory  inner 
situations,  however  real  such  situations  may  be,  are  not  the 
only  types  of  action  that  are  significant  in  life.  Much  of 
the  thought-action  which  furnishes  the  content  of  an  in 
telligent  life  has  no  immediate  reference  to  overt  action,  and 
possibly  in  most  cases  when  the  act  is  being  performed,  there 
is  no  immediate  or  remote  intention  of  producing  results 
outside  of  the  present  consciousness.  And  much  of  the 
thought  that  has  been  responsible  for  past  human  achieve 
ment  has  been  obliged  to  lie  dormant  as  value  until  future 
situations  arose  in  which  it  might  become  practical.  This 
means  that  thought  may  and  does  determine  the  situations 
in  which  it  is  to  be  useful,  and  while  it  may  have  grown  out 
of  previous  situations,  its  contact  neither  with  those  situa 
tions  nor  with  the  situations  in  which  it  is  to  be  useful  is 
known  to  it  when  the  thought-act  is  accomplished.  Thought 
is  then  often  an  end  in  itself,  so  far  as  its  own  act  is  con 
cerned,  and  this  is  true  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  it  may  turn 
out  to  be  useful.  That  it  may  turn  out  to  be  useful  is  evi 
dence  of  further  thought.  Granting  that  all  thought  is 
sooner  or  later  useful  and  has  connection  with  practical 
situations,  it  still  may  be  argued  that  those  situations  are 
not  consciously  involved  in  the  thought  process  while  it  is 
going  on.  But  this  is  one  of  the  cases  where  appeal  to  the 
unconscious  will  settle  all  difficulties.  And  the  settlement 
on  these  terms  looks  very  much  like  a  refusal  to  recognize 
any  problem.  The  tendency  to  refuse  to  recognize  problems 
is  often  shown  by  those  who  argue  most  strenuously  for  the 
problematical  character  of  all  thought. 

This  argument,  it  must  be  confessed,  begins  to  savor  too 
much  of  old-fashioned  '  reason.'  What  we  are  after,  it  is 
insisted,  is  to  force  reason  to  make  room  for  other  forms  of 
experience  like  feeling  and  will.  As  directed  against  a  con 
ception  of  reason  which  makes  it  act  like  an  efficient  cause  to 
produce  results  ideally  out  of  nothing;  as  against  a  reason 


264  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

that  permeates  the  whole  of  what  is,  reducing  what  is  to 
eternal  rationality;  as  against  reason  which  is  regarded  as 
anything  else  than  the  life-process  in  the  individual  human 
being,  the  criticism  is  accepted  as  valid.  But  to  many 
persons  it  has  not  occurred  to  make  of  reason  anything  other 
than  reflection  held  as  dominant  in  the  life-process  of  the 
individual.  It  is  not  necessary  to  think  of  it  as  separated 
from  the  life-process  and  somehow  eternally  hostile  to  it. 
It  may  be  said  frankly  that  there  is  no  'reason'  any  more 
than  there  is  a  principle  of  synderesis.  Still  it  may  be  allow 
able  to  use  the  term  to  designate  what  is  most  characteristic 
in  the  life-process,  even  if  that  function  should  turn  out  to 
be  on  occasion  'irrational,'  as  it  doubtless  often  does.  In 
any  case  we  have  no  right  to  impose  on  that  function  the 
obligation  to  guarantee  results,  even  at  the  expense  of  sub 
verting  the  world,  as  we  do  when  we  insist  that  since  reason 
ordinarily  functions  in  an  orderly  way,  it  must  therefore 
guarantee  a  world  rationalized  throughout  as  a  product  of 
original  design. 

But  if  we  remember  that  by  reason  we  mean  simply  the 
fact  that  memory  and  imagination  function  together  in  the 
life-process  of  the  individual,  the  difficulties  mentioned  above 
will  be  met  by  anticipation.  By  memory  and  imagination 
we  mean  no  mythical  entities  or  powers  or  faculties,  but 
simply  the  fact  that  the  past  is  envisaged  and  the  future  is 
constructed.  Recalling  further  the  factors  that  furnish  the 
content  for  both  processes,  it  will  be  clear  that  there  is  no 
single  aspect  of  life  that  is  not  represented  in  'reason'  as 
we  now  understand  it.  Memory  is  largely  the  feeling  that 
accompanies  and  characterizes  the  recognition  of  'action' 
implied  in  spatial  and  temporal  relations  experienced  pre 
viously,  and  in  connection  with  imagination  these  feelings 
function  as  plans  in  further  action  designed  to  accomplish  a 
satisfaction  or  fulfill  a  purpose.  Thus  memory  cannot  be 
described  without  involving  the  imagination,  and  the  de 
scription  of  imagination  involves  memory.  And  the  two 
processes  taken  together  constitute  the  one  invariable  ele 
ment  within  the  life-process.  This  common  element  has 


IDEA  AND  ACTION  265 

been  inadequately  described,  and,  under  the  name  of  'cog 
nition,'  has  been  represented  as  a  free  cause,  but  that  does 
not  argue  away  the  fact  that  what  is  better  called  recognition 
is  a  factor  common  to  all  experience  that  is  significant  or 
that  may  become  significant. 

It  thus  seems  that  'intellectualism'  in  some  sense  or  in 
some  degree  is  unavoidable,  and  the  problem  is  to  find  the 
sense  in  which,  and  the  degree  to  which,  the  principle  of  rea 
son  will  stand  emphasis.  That  it  has  been  over-emphasized 
in  the  past  is  shown  by  the  criticisms  for  which  empiricism 
has  forced  recognition.  A  more  or  less  satisfactory  balance 
has,  however,  been  reached  between  the  intellectualists  and 
the  empiricists,  and  the  problem  now  seems  to  be  whether 
further  concessions  must  be  made  on  the  part  of  reason  in 
the  interest  of  action.  The  point  of  view  of  this  essay  is  that 
already  the  impulse  to  do  in  practical  affairs  has  been  over 
worked  as  an  epistemological  motive,  and  what  is  necessary 
now  is  that  the  attempt  should  be  made  to  think  out  a 
proper  balance  and  harmony  in  the  present  chaos  of  life- 
processes.  A  philosophy  of  action,  particularly  in  the  de 
generate  form  of  efficiency  philosophy  now  employed  to  dis 
place  ethics  as  the  science  of  practice,  may  work  satisfactorily 
as  a  principle  in  business  where  men  are  things  or  parts  of 
machines;  but  in  education  and  politics  and  ethics  where 
men  are,  or  hope  to  be,  men,  something  is  yet  to  be  learned 
from  the  doctrine  of  'pure  ideas.' 


SOME  PRACTICAL  SUBSTITUTES  FOR  THINKING 
HARVEY  GATES  TOWNSEND 

DEFINITIONS  of  judgment  have  been  taken  out  of  the 
mouths  of  metaphysicians  and  logicians  and  so  transformed 
by  biology  and  psychology  that  considerable  imagination  is 
required  before  we  can  get  back  to  a  common  understanding. 
The  older  logicians  discussed  judgment  in  terms  of  form  and 
content.  Under  the  first  head  formal  logic  has  flourished  in 
the  schools  for  many  centuries;  under  the  second,  advanced 
logical  and  metaphysical  speculation  (sometimes  called  epis- 
temology)  has  been  the  greatest  single  motive  in  modern 
philosophy,  at  least  since  the  days  of  Kant.  The  great 
philosophical  question  has  been,  Is  a  judgment  true?  It 
seems  that  this  question  obtains  its  fascination  by  appealing 
to  disinterested  motives:  the  love  of  truth  for  its  own  sake, 
the  desire  to  know,  the  hope  of  satisfying  the  ultimate  ques 
tions  of  the  human  mind  regarding  truth,  beauty,  and  good 
ness.  It  is  a  question  concerning  the  real  world  and  also 
concerning  our  knowledge  of  the  real  world. 

With  the  ascendency  of  the  biological  sciences,  however, 
new  categories  have  taken  the  place  of  the  old  ones  and  the 
meaning  of  judgment  has  been  transformed  before  our  very 
eyes.  The  omnivorous  dogma  of  the  survival  of  the  fit  has 
consumed  the  distinctions  formerly  supposed  to  exist  between 
man  and  his  fellow  creatures.  The  quasi-theological  phrases 
of  our  fathers  representing  man  as  a  creature  able  to  know 
the  reality  of  things  and  to  share  divine  purposes  have  been 
replaced  by  the  new  estimate  of  man  as  a  'psycho-physical 
organism.'  This  means  that  whatever  a  man  does  is  to  be 
understood  and  interpreted  no  longer  by  reference  to  his  sup 
posed  destiny,  but  rather  by  reference  to  his  recorded  past. 
If  he  shaves,  stands  with  his  back  to  the  wall,  wears  clothes, 
associates  with  his  fellow  men,  makes  war,  establishes  gov- 


SOME  PRACTICAL  SUBSTITUTES  FOR  THINKING  267 

ernments,  strives  to  be  reasonable,  hopes  for  heaven,  or 
saves  a  child  at  the  cost  of  his  own  life,  it  is  perforce  because 
these  acts  have  survival  value  and  not  because  he  judges 
them  to  be  worthy.  In  fact  his  judgment  itself  is  but  an 
other  unconscious  means  of  survival.  More  broadly  speak 
ing,  mind,  the  archetype  of  judgment,  is  transformed  into 
a  function  of  cellular  matter,  developed  in  the  struggle  for 
existence  and  preserved  automatically  by  its  survival  value. 
"Biologists,"  says  Hobhouse,  "may  be  careful  to  eschew 
metaphysics  and  may  avoid  the  charge  of  materialism  by  a 
judicious  selection  of  phrases.  None  the  less  it  lies  in  the 
nature  of  the  biological  treatment  to  think  of  mental  activ 
ity  like  all  activity,  like  muscular  contraction  or  glandular 
secretion,  like  respiration  or  digestion,  as  the  function  of  a 
structure."  l  Mind  has  thus  become  an  instrument  of  the 
body. 

In  such  an  intellectual  atmosphere  the  old  question,  Is  a 
judgment  true?  seems  strangely  unmeaning,  or  if  it  still 
has  meaning,  it  is  at  least  treated  as  unimportant.  By  a 
little  shuffling  in  the  definition  of  the  word  true,  however,  it 
may  be  made  the  equivalent  of  useful,  whereupon  the  ques 
tion  becomes  transformed  into  one  which  the  biologist  will 
understand  and  accept.  The  coin  of  this  realm  is  life,  and 
the  way  to  test  a  judgment  is  to  find  out  how  much  life  it  will 
buy.  In  such  calculations  the  dominant  consideration  is 
quantity,  and  qualitative  distinctions  seem  irrelevant.  Even 
though  this  interpretation  of  judgment  is  not  wholly  satis 
factory,  it  is  not  my  purpose  to  deplore  the  interpretation 
but  to  understand  it  and  to  point  out  its  practical  bearings. 
The  most  obvious  result  of  this  view  of  judgment  is  to  fasten 
attention  on  the  function  of  judgment  as  a  means  to  a 
further  end  and  to  obscure,  perhaps  all  but  obliterate,  the 
value  of  judgment  as  a  process  and  an  end  in  itself.  It  is  as 
if  one  who  set  out  to  achieve  the  reasonable  life  had  come  to 
seek  life  first  with  reason  only  as  a  means  thereto. 

Before  self-consciousness  became  a  myth,  some  persons, 
after  a  debauch  of  introspection,  used  to  testify  that  a  deep 
1  Development  and  Purpose,  p.  8. 


268  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

and  lasting  satisfaction  was  to  be  derived  from  thinking  for 
oneself.  On  its  psychological  side  thinking  has  in  it  some 
thing  akin  to  the  instinct  of  possession.  To  be  able  to  say 
truly,  '  I  think,'  is  to  take  a  long  step  forward  in  self-respect. 
The  desire  for  the  possession  of  ideas  is  as  keen  as  the  desire 
for  the  possession  of  things.  Whoever  has  seen  the  compre 
hensive  smile  of  a  child  who  has  learned  to  do  something  for 
himself  need  not  rely  upon  his  own  experience  to  be  convinced 
that  self-activity  brings  rich  satisfactions,  irrespective  of  the 
results  of  that  activity.  Psychologically  the  process  of 
thinking  brings  the  permanent  satisfactions  of  self-knowledge 
and  self-control  and  may  in  so  far  be  rated  as  a  good  in  itself. 
But  the  psychological  significance  of  thinking  cannot  be 
long  separated  from  its  ethical  or  political  significance.  At 
this  point,  at  least,  thinking  seems  to  be  primarily  an  end 
rather  than  a  means  to  some  further  and  external  end.  In 
spite  of  the  prevailing  utilitarianism  of  British  ethical  theory, 
the  older  dictum  of  Kant,  that  nothing  is  good  except  the 
good  will,  still  carries  conviction  to  plain  people  because  it 
is  based  upon  a  very  common  and  homely  experience.  This 
experience  may  be  called  the  experience  of  personal  re 
sponsibility,  as  distinguished  from  another  experience  which 
we  may  call  the  experience  of  observing  the  results  of  overt 
action.  The  latter  experience  may  be  temporarily  ab 
stracted  from  the  former.  That  is  to  say,  the  person  may 
take  the  attitude  of  an  impartial  spectator.  Whether  the 
act  be  his  own  or  another's,  the  effect  of  the  act  works  itself 
out  in  the  same  terms.  Morality  on  this  plane  is  capable  of 
scientific  generalization  and  control.  Personal  responsibility 
need  hardly  be  mentioned.  The  experience  of  personal 
responsibility,  however,  is  more  immediate  and  more  con 
crete.  It  is  more  immediate  in  the  sense  that  it  is  an  un- 
analysed  idea  developed  without  the  machinery  of  science  or 
scientific  method.  It  is  closer  to  feeling  and  aesthetic  ap 
preciation  than  it  is  to  logic  or  technique.  It  is  concrete  be 
cause  it  is  completely,  although  not  explicitly,  bound  up 
with  the  objective  aspect  of  moral  action.  If  we  start  with 
the  mass  feeling  of  guilt  or  of  essential  goodness,  we  can 


SOME  PRACTICAL  SUBSTITUTES  FOR  THINKING  269 

easily  and  must  necessarily  raise  the  issue  of  causes,  results, 
and  connections.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  we  start  with  the 
mechanism  of  morals,  we  may  be  permanently  caught  within 
it  and  see  no  need  of  escape.  We  get  into  an  infinite  regress 
which  will  never  carry  us  beyond  itself.  Thus,  a  judge,  ex 
cept  for  court  traditions,  might  examine  the  overt  act  of  a 
criminal  without  reference  to  the  criminal.  In  case  he  looks 
upon  the  accused  as  a  link  in  a  chain  of  social  unpleasant 
nesses  rather  than  as  a  person,  he  might  even  go  further  and 
sentence  the  criminal  without  reference  to  the  criminal. 

Perhaps  modern  legal  procedure  tends  in  the  direction  of 
dehumanizing  morality.  No  one  can  tell  where  it  will  lead. 
The  other  view, — that  of  personal  responsibility, — is  usually 
associated  with  our  religious  or  theological  heritage.  It 
starts  from  the  assumption  that  "all  other  values  are  rela 
tive  to  value  for,  of,  or  in  a  person."  l  From  this  point  of 
view  a  person  is  not  a  'psycho-physical  organism'  but  a 
judging,  unitary  center  of  value.  It  seems,  moreover,  quite 
absurd  to  leave  out  the  word  judging  in  such  a  formula. 
To  leave  it  out  would  look  in  the  wrong  direction  to  discover 
the  center  of  value.  Without  reference  to  personal  judgment 
value  becomes  a  mere  pawn  or  symbol.  Like  our  currency, 
it  must  be  secured  somewhere  for  its  face  value.  Like  our 
currency,  also,  it  is  secured  in  the  last  analysis  in  the  intan 
gible  region  of  faith,  good  will,  and  personal  responsibility. 

The  indefinite  multiplication  of  such  centers  of  value  has 
been  taken  to  be  the  goal  of  democratic  institutions.  This 
multiplication,  however,  cannot  be  directly  secured  by  in 
creasing  the  birth  rate,  or  lowering  the  death  rate,  or  avoid 
ing  devastation  and  war,  or  increasing  the  product  of  fac 
tories.  It  can  be  secured,  if  at  all,  by  the  hard  and  inefficient 
road  of  trial  and  error  for  each  person  or  generation  of  per 
sons.  To  be  sure,  the  trial  and  error  need  not  be  about  the 
same  details  of  mastery,  but  trial  and  error  there  must  be 
wherever  persons  are  to  exist.  This  is  a  symbol  of  the  per 
petual  struggle  of  mind  to  master  the  conditions  of  its  lasting 
satisfaction.  Judgment,  even  for  the  biologist,  functions 
1  Green,  Prolegomena,  §  184. 


270  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

only  in  contact  with  the  new  and  untried  present.  Biology 
declares  that  judgment  was  developed  in  the  face  of  a 
rapidly  shifting  and  hostile  environment.  The  creatures 
other  than  man  who  for  any  reason  live  in  a  static  environ 
ment  have  no  need  for  judgment  or  thinking.  Man,  however, 
with  his  easy  locomotion  and  versatility  on  land  and  water, 
must  have  perished  but  for  his  wits.  It  is  upon  this  capacity 
of  man  that  ethical  value  rests.  If  this  statement  is  not 
true  of  all  ethical  value,  it  certainly  is  true  of  the  first  kind 
mentioned  above,  that  is,  the  personal  kind  of  morality. 
This  is  the  ideal  of  freedom  running  through  all  philosophy 
from  the  Greeks  to  our  own  day,  the  freedom  of  autonomous 
action.  Autonomous  action  is  nothing  but  action  accom 
panied  by  conscious  purpose  made  more  and  more  free  as 
complete  awareness  of  the  whole  situation  is  approached. 
With  this  view  of  morality  must  go  a  faith  in  the  ultimate 
unity  of  wills,  a  faith  that  as  many  persons  become  more  self- 
conscious  and  more  intelligent  they  will  become  more  har 
monious  and  unified.  This  is  the  hope  of  a  democracy,  but 
it  is  also  the  despair  of  a  democracy.  The  way  to  such  a  goal 
seems  infinitely  slow  and  uncertain.  The  goal  itself  may  be 
a  mirage.  Every  generation  and  every  individual  at  some 
time  despairs  of  this  goal,  or,  what  amounts  to  the  same 
thing,  conceives  the  idea  of  a  short  cut  to  the  desired  haven, 
a  royal  road  to  human  felicity.  This  is  the  attitude  that 
has  led  to  the  substitution  of  other  mental  processes  for 
thinking.  It  is  the  purpose  of  this  paper  to  point  out  some 
of  the  substitutes  at  present  offered  as  panaceas  for  social 
evil  and  to  suggest  in  what  respect  they  attempt  to  avoid 
the  issues  implied  in  the  foregoing  statement  of  the  nature 
of  judgment. 

The  reader  of  educational  discussion  must  have  been  im 
pressed  with  the  great  frequency  of  reference  to  habit- 
formation  as  the  chief  aim  of  the  common  school.  The  con 
tention  does  not  always  appear  in  just  this  form.  Sometimes 
it  comes  under  the  guise  of  drill  and  sometimes  under  the 
name  of  vocational  training.  One  does  not  have  to  take 
Rousseau  too  literally  when  he  says,  "The  only  habit  which 


SOME  PRACTICAL  SUBSTITUTES  FOR  THINKING  271 

a  child  should  be  allowed  to  form  is  that  of  forming  none,"  1 
in  order  to  grasp  the  essential  truth  which  such  an  extreme 
statement  conveys.  Rousseau's  theory  in  this  is  democratic 
or  it  is  nothing.  We  are  to  understand  that  he  considers 
habit  a  poor  substitute  for  that  creative,  personal  activity 
which  he  calls  nature.  Wherever  there  is  an  uncritical  de 
mand  that  the  school  prepare  its  pupils  to  fit  into  the  in 
dustrial  or  economic  status  quo,  there  is  involved  the  issue 
of  habit  versus  thinking.  This  fact  is  often  vaguely  dis 
cerned  and  as  a  consequence  ineffectively  attacked.  Aside 
from  individual  differences,  all  systems  of  industrial  or  voca 
tional  training  in  the  common  schools  seek  to  develop  the 
skill  demanded  by  industry  and  practical  economic  condi 
tions.  The  school  is  supposed  to  look  forward  to  discover  the 
environment  of  the  pupil  and  then  to  set  itself  the  task  of  fit 
ting  the  pupil  for  the  environment;  in  doing  this  the  school 
neglects  not  only  and  perhaps  least  of  all  the  right  of  an 
individual  to  his  own  mature  judgment  in  the  matter,  but 
it  neglects  the  incalculable  and  unpredictable  nature  of  a 
changing  environment.  We  are  solemnly  told  that  country 
schools,  for  instance,  should  confine  their  efforts  to  the 
training  of  farm  hands,  yet  the  imagination  is  not  unable  to 
see  the  farmer's  child  in  a  radically  different  environment 
during  his  mature  life.  The  teacher  sets  himself  up  to  think 
for  the  pupil  and  to  crystallize  his  thought  in  the  pupil  in 
the  form  of  skill  or  habit.  When  teachers  get  a  little  wiser, 
they  may  think  so  well  that  the  rest  of  the  people  will  not 
have  to  think  at  all.  The  antidote  for  this  school  theory  is 
to  teach  the  pupil,  whether  in  city  or  country,  to  think  and 
judge  and  will  for  himself.  That  is  all  very  well,  say  the 
advocates  of  vocational  training,  but  how  shall  we  accom 
plish  this  idealistic  aim  without  danger  to  society?  The 
answer  must  be  that  it  cannot  be  accomplished  without 
danger  to  society.  Give  to  each  the  tools  of  knowledge  and 
let  him  use  them  as  and  when  and  how  he  will,  so  that  life 
for  him  and  for  us  all  is  then  an  adventure  rather  than  a 
prearranged,  *  safety-first'  affair. 

*  Smile,  Bk.  I. 


272  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

I  would  not  be  understood  to  say  that  thinking  cannot  be 
developed  along  with  and  through  vocational  training,  but 
it  is  important  to  recognize  the  development  of  thinking  as 
the  aim  and  not  the  means  of  vocational  training.  As  sug 
gested  above,  Rousseau's  epigram  cannot  be  taken  literally. 
No  one  in  his  senses  pretends  that  education  can  function 
without  habit,  but  we  are  perfectly  sure  that  habits  can  and 
do  function  without  education.  No  habit  is  good  enough  to 
be  a  perpetual  substitute  for  thinking.  And  this  is  precisely 
because  habit  is  thinking — dead.  It  is  thinking  petrified  by 
contact  with  a  static  environment.  When  the  environment 
changes,  habit  becomes  an  evil  positively  interfering  with 
the  good  of  the  organism.  But  this  is  not  all;  biology  and 
ethics  go  this  far  together.  Ethics  may  now  insist  that  there 
is  value  in  the  freedom  of  new  and  living  thinking  quite  apart 
from  its  service  in  saving  the  biological  organism.  The  ques 
tion  is  not,  Does  it  preserve  life?  but,  Does  it  make  life  worth 
preserving?  We  might  make  the  habit  perpetually  effective, 
but  only  at  the  cost  of  making  life  perpetually  the  same. 
The  inner  experience  of  growth  and  action  could  not  be 
known.  In  a  word,  all  the  pragmatic  results  of  thinking 
might  be  secured  in  an  individual  through  habit  without 
securing  one  moment  of  valuable  existence. 

Another  substitute  for  thinking  may  be  presented  under 
the  head  of  social  control.  The  study  of  psychology,  for 
instance,  has  made  it  possible  for  a  leader  to  relieve  his  fol 
lowers  of  all  thinking.  The  same  result  that  may  be  secured 
by  the  aristocracy  of  military  control  may  also  be  secured  by 
the  more  subtile  control  of  suggestion.  The  soldier  who  puts 
on  the  uniform  puts  off  the  right  and  eventually  the  ability 
to  think.  If  he  thinks,  one  of  two  things  will  happen :  he  will 
either  be  put  in  command  or  in  the  guard  house.  The  former 
positions  are  rigidly  limited;  the  latter  are  potentially  in 
finite.  It  is,  therefore,  the  rule  that  thinking  is  uncalled  for. 
Democratic  society  may  congratulate  itself  if  it  has  escaped 
the  evils  of  militarism,  for  those  evils  are  the  negation  of  the 
aim  of  democracy.  However  this  may  be,  the  psychology  of 
social  control  offers  a  practical  substitute  for  military  control. 


SOME  PRACTICAL  SUBSTITUTES  FOR  THINKING  273 

In  fact,  military  force  is  only  an  early  and  particularly  gross 
form  of  social  control. 

It  is  immaterial  that  in  the  long  run  social  control  may  de 
feat  its  primary  intention.  An  advertising  manager  is  hired 
to  sell  goods  by  means  of  suggestion  and  plausible  assertion. 
Advertising  may  indirectly  affect  the  character  of  the  prod 
uct,  but  in  the  first  instance  it  has  nothing  to  do  with  the 
thing  it  advertises.  Its  purpose  it  to  turn  some  people  into 
money  in  order  to  satisfy  the  aims  of  some  other  people.  In 
so  far  as  this  is  true,  it  is  fundamentally  averse  to  the  de 
velopment  of  individual  thinkers  and  thus  may  be  said  to 
run,  superficially  at  least,  counter  to  the  aim  of  democracy. 
Like  habit,  social  control  is  offered  as  a  substitute  for  think 
ing.  The  difference  between  the  two  is  that  habit  indicates 
the  presence  of  thinking  at  some  time  in  the  individual  who 
uses  the  habit,  while  social  control  is  the  thought  of  one 
individual  imposed  from  without  upon  another. 

The  case  of  advertising  serves  as  an  illustration  of  all  forms 
of  social  control.  A  certain  kind  of  sociologist  is  pathetically 
concerned  in  securing  the  results  of  his  thinking  for  other 
people.  His  generosity  may  be  conceded  without  admitting 
that  he  serves  anybody  well  but  himself.  He  desires  to 
think  for  others  because  he  supposes  that  thinking  is  of 
instrumental  value  and  worth  whatever  it  will  buy,  rather 
than  a  process  of  spiritual  evolution,  of  value  only  to  the 
person  of  the  spirit.  Many  social  reforms  fall  upon  society 
as  dead  weights  crushing  out  the  real  life  of  the  spirit  because 
they  are  not  the  product  of  spiritual  travail  in  the  persons 
for  whom  they  are  intended.  Indeed,  they  are  not  intended 
by  those  to  whom  they  are  applied.  Any  social  control  that 
stops  short  of  intelligent  co-operation  is  a  failure.  It  may  get 
the  result  of  thinking,  but  unless  it  gets  also  the  process  of 
thinking,  it  is  only  a  mill-stone  hung  about  the  neck. 

Another  growing  means  of  suppressing  the  growth  and 
vigor  of  thinking  is  the  cult  of  the  expert.  It  seems  that  the 
world  needs  a  periodical  demonstration  of  the  fallibility  of 
the  expert.  In  these  times  it  has  taken  the  form  of  the 
ridiculous  pronunciamentos  of  famous  scholars  regarding 


274  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

world  issues.  It  is  not  enough  merely  to  say  that  they  have 
ventured  out  of  the  field  in  which  they  are  expert.  The  fault 
inheres  in  the  nature  of  expert  knowledge,  for  how  else  can 
expert  knowledge  be  defined  than  by  using  the  trappings  of 
dogmatism?  It  has  been  said, — with  how  much  truth  I  do 
not  pretend  to  know, — that  the  mantle  of  dogmatism  is 
slipping  from  the  shoulders  of  the  priest  and  resting  upon 
the  shoulders  of  the  scientist.  If  such  a  position  offends  by 
its  obscurantism,  judgment  should  not  be  passed  lightly  until 
the  characteristic  manner  of  science  has  been  recalled.  What 
science  is  presented  without  recourse  to  "it  was  once  sup 
posed  but  we  now  know"?  Or,  the  "opinion"  of  others  is 
contrasted  with  the  "truth"  of  science.  The  demand  is 
made  that  those  who  are  expert  should  be  given  complete 
control  of  public  or  institutional  programs,  and  much  amuse 
ment  is  had  over  the  notion  of  a  grocer  or  a  teamster  on  the 
school  committee.  But  why?  The  implicit  answer  is  that 
a  grocer  is  just  a  grocer  and  nothing  more.  The  presumption 
is  also  that  members  of  school  boards  must  be  members  of 
school  boards  and  nothing  more.  This  is  a  characteristic 
assumption  of  the  expert  and  is  contrary  to  some  rather 
broad  human  points  of  view.  Even  if  we  should  grant  that  a 
person  expert  in  school  administration  would  make  a  better 
school  committeeman,  which  may  be  doubted,  still  there  is  a 
large  question  unanswered.  It  is,  Suppose  the  grocer  is  to 
be  just  a  grocer,  and  the  carpenter  just  a  carpenter,  and  so 
on  with  all  the  rest,  must  it  not  lead  to  a  static  condition  of 
society  in  which  each  is  less  than  himself  because  he  is  not 
more?  This  is  the  paradox  which  the  expert  seems  never  to 
grasp.  Thinking  is  a  process,  not  a  result. 

To  those  who  read  only  the  best  and  greatest  science  the 
above  description  will  seem  more  like  a  caricature  than  a 
portrait.  It  is  in  fact  not  the  great  scientist  who  loses  touch 
with  reality  in  developing  his  power  of  analysis.  I  am  speak 
ing  of  the  expert  and  his  follower  and  with  this  purpose  only 
in  mind:  to  suggest  that  expert  knowledge  is  a  shield  of  ig 
norance  and  a  substitute  for  judgment.  Probably  the  expert 
is  not  more  to  be  blamed  for  this  attitude  than  the  rest  of  us, 


SOME  PRACTICAL  SUBSTITUTES  FOR  THINKING  275 

for  even  otherwise  sensible  people  who  possess  a  bit  of  know- 
edge  soon  begin  to  treat  it  as  a  finality.  This  is  involved  in 
the  distinction  which  we  make  between  thinking  and  know 
ing.  The  expert  is  the  one  who  knows  and  knows  that  he 
knows.  Such  an  attitude  is  dogmatism  and  dogmatism  of 
the  most  fatal  variety.  Dogmatism  is  about  the  most  com 
mon  substitute  for  thinking  and  is  the  bitterest  enemy  of 
democratic  government.  It  matters  very  little  whether  it 
takes  the  form  of  the  idols  of  the  theater  or  the  idols  of 
science,  for  scientific  truth  is  just  like  any  other  truth:  as 
soon  as  it  is  accepted  it  must  be  revised.  It  is  this  process  of 
revision  which  I  have  spoken  of  as  judgment  or  thinking, 
which  has  worth  independent  of  its  pragmatic  product. 

A  typical  outcropping  of  the  cult  of  the  expert  has  been 
naively  expressed  by  a  recent  writer  in  the  discussion  of 
academic  freedom.  The  expert  usually  stops  in  his  theory 
with  the  praise  of  expert  farmers,  mechanics,  tradesmen,  and 
statesmen,  but  this  writer  bluntly  tells  us  that  "it  is  a  decree 
of  human  nature,  a  principle  ever  more  emphasized  by  the 
growing  intensity  and  complexity  of  modern  society,  that 
a  few  should  do  the  thinking  for  the  many."  1  At  a  somewhat 
later  point  in  his  discussion  he  expresses  the  logic  of  his  own 
position  in  the  remark,  "The  goal  [of  democracy]  must  be  a 
social  order  in  which  equality  of  opportunity  is  made  the 
instrument  for  assuring  a  dynamic,  progressive  society  based 
upon  socially  valuable  inequalities."  2  A  better  statement 
could  hardly  be  made  of  the  theory  that  thinking  has  instru 
mental  and  merely  instrumental  value.  But  democracy 
requires  a  theory  that  thinking  is  of  value  as  a  goal,  not  as  a 
mere  means  to  a  goal.  If  experts  are  to  do  our  thinking  for 
us,  they  would  be  put  into  exclusive  possession  of  the  only 
valuable  existence.  It  is  possible  to  show  that  practical 
evils  would  flow  from  turning  over  the  thinking  to  the  few, 
largely  because  the  few  who  think  also  desire,  but  it  is  not 
to  the  present  purpose. 

Thinking  is  theoretically  and  practically  the  hardest  and 
most  unpleasant  task  that  the  natural  adult  faces.  Bio- 

1  School  and  Society,  Vol.  Ill,  1917,  p.  625.  2  Ibid.,  p.  629. 


276  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

logically  it  means  lack  of  adjustment  and  danger.  The 
course  of  least  resistance  must  be  abandoned  for  the  good 
of  the  organism  when  it  is  confronted  with  a  new  situation. 
It  has  been  the  purpose  of  this  paper  to  set  forth  one  or  two 
common  experiences  from  this  point  of  view  and  to  suggest 
in  what  manner  the  substitute  will  never  quite  serve  for  the 
original.  If  an  individual  is  face  to  face  with  a  situation  that 
demands  thought,  he  will  at  first  try  to  escape.  He  may  say, 
I  have  thought  (habit)  or,  Another  has  thought  for  me 
(dogmatism).  The  situation  will  answer,  That  does  not 
count;  you  must  think  for  yourself  now.  There  is  even, 
therefore,  a  biological  necessity  for  individual  thinking,  but 
in  the  realm  of  biology  the  value  involved  is  mere  life  and 
might  be  secured  by  habit  or  by  expert  knowledge;  or,  if 
these  two  could  not  save  life,  the  loss  would  be  slight.  In 
ethics  and  politics,  however,  the  value  involved  is  a  way  of 
life,  and  in  this  case  to  offer  a  substitute  for  thinking  is  to 
lose  all  that  one  has  to  lose.  In  the  first  field  one  loses  only 
if  the  habit  or  information  fails;  in  the  second  field  one  loses 
whether  the  substitute  fails  or  succeeds. 

Under  the  influence  of  biological  science  we  have  gradually 
come  to  think  of  judgment  as  a  mere  means  of  survival  and 
this  theory  has  led  directly  and  surely  to  the  conclusion  that, 
if  we  can  get  the  result  without  the  hard  discipline  of  think 
ing,  we  make  a  good  bargain.  When  this  is  taken  together 
with  the  suppression  of  consciousness  in  psychology  and  the 
decadence  of  individual  responsibility  before  the  law,  it  is  no 
wonder  that  mechanical  efficiency  is  judged  to  be  more 
worthy  than  personal  expansion  and  intellectual  develop 
ment. 


SELFHOOD 
EMIL  CARL  WILM 

SINCE  Hume's  justly  celebrated  discussion  of  the  self, 
many  efforts  have  been  made  to  render  the  theory  of  the 
self  more  articulate  and  to  place  it  upon  a  broader  basis  of 
empirical  fact.  If  the  results  appear  disproportionate  to  the 
length  of  the  discussion  and  the  prominence  of  the  partici 
pants  in  it,  one  reason  for  this  is  doubtless  that  there  has 
been  little  agreement  either  as  to  the  precise  objects  under 
discussion,  or  as  to  the  methods  competent  for  the  solution 
of  the  problems  at  issue.  The  mooted  question  of  the 
prevalence  of  self-consciousness  in  experience,  one  phase 
only  of  the  general  self-problem,  is  a  case  in  point.  "Das: 
Ich  denke,"  wrote  Kant,  "muss  alle  meine  Vorstellungen 
begleiten  konnen."  This  view,  which  in  recent  discussions 
is  emphatically  expressed  by  Professor  Calkins  and  other 
psychologists  of  standing,  meets  with  a  flat  denial  from  other 
writers  equally  skilled  in  introspection  and  equally  accredited 
spokesmen  of  modern  psychology.  "All  consciousness," 
asserts  Professor  Calkins,  "is  self-consciousness,  that  is,  one 
never  is  conscious  at  all  without  an  awareness,  however 
vague,  confused,  unanalyzed,  and  unexpressed,  of  oneself- 
being-conscious."  J  Again,  "always  in  being  conscious  I  am 
aware  not  only  of  myself  but  of  other-than-self  (either  per 
sonal  or  impersonal)."  2  This  view  is  rejected  by  James,  on 
the  other  hand,  as  "a  perfectly  wanton  assumption."  "As 
well  might  I  contend  that  I  cannot  dream  without  dreaming 
that  I  dream,  swear  without  swearing  that  I  swear,  deny 

1  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific  Methods,  Vol.  V, 
1908,  p.  68. 

2  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XVII,  1908,  p.  274,  and  in  other  places. 
The  position  is  of  course  more  sweeping  than  Kant's,  who  treated  the 
omnipresence  of  consciousness  as  only  potential. 


278  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

without  denying  that  I  deny,  as  maintain  that  I  cannot 
know  without  knowing  that  I  know.  I  may  have  either 
acquaintance-with,  or  knowledge-about,  an  object  O  without 
thinking  about  myself  at  all."  1  Equally  emphatic  is  the 
rejection  of  the  omnipresence  theory  on  the  part  of  Professor 
Titchener:  "It  is  often  said,  in  the  psychological  text-books, 
that  a  conscious  self  forms  the  permanent  background  of 
consciousness,  and  that  we  have  but  to  direct  our  attention 
to  this  background,  to  bring  the  self  to  full  realisation.  The 
statement  is  made  so  frequently  and  so  dogmatically  that 
the  author  inclines  to  suspect  the  existence  of  individual 
differences.  It  may  be  that  some  minds  are  cast,  so  to  say, 
in  a  personal  mould,  and  that  others  are  relatively  imper 
sonal.  In  the  author's  experience,  the  conscious  self,  while 
it  may  always  be  constructed  by  a  voluntary  effort,  is  of 
comparatively  rare  occurrence." 

The  real  reason,  however,  for  the  fundamental  disagree 
ment  (I  venture  to  think)  is  not  so  much  the  existence  of 
individual  differences,  although  these  doubtless  prevail,  as 
the  fact  that  in  the  discussion  of  selfhood,  as  in  so  many 
other  philosophical  debates,  there  is  usually  little  pretense 
of  agreement  as  to  the  definitions  of  the  terms  employed  in 
the  discussion.  Self  is  a  broad  and  loose  term,  and  it  would 
seem  a  matter  of  the  first  importance,  in  any  consideration 
of  the  subject,  to  indicate  in  advance  just  what  meaning  a 
writer  intends  when  he  uses  the  term.  This  meaning  will 
at  the  outset  have  to  be  somewhat  arbitrarily  chosen  and 
may  in  the  end  prove  indefensible;  but  whether  it  is  defensi 
ble  or  not  could  never  be  shown,  unless  it  is  first  understood. 
It  will  be  the  attempt  of  the  present  paper  (i)  to  restate 
somewhat  systematically  certain  distinctions  which  have 
been  generally  recognized  by  those  who  have  dealt  with  the 
self-problem,  and  (2)  in  the  light  of  these  distinctions  to 
reconsider  briefly  in  what  sense,  if  any,  the  self  exists. 

According  to  a  time-honored  view,  deeply  imbedded  in 

1  Principles  of  Psychology,  Vol.  I,  p.  274. 

2  A  Text-Book  of  Psychology,  p.  544.    See  also  the  same  author's  excel 
lent  discussion  of  the  subject  in  his  A  Beginner's  Psychology,  Ch.  XII. 


SELFHOOD  279 

the  language  of  common  sense  and  elaborately  articulated  in 
philosophy,  experience  is  bipolar  in  its  constitution.  It  con 
tains  within  itself  the  double  aspect  of  knower  and  known. 
There  is  the  empirical  self,  the  content  or  object  side  of  con 
sciousness,  composed  of  so-called  states  or  processes  of  con 
sciousness  like  perceptions,  memories,  emotions,  and  conative 
experiences,  and  the  subject,  the  transcendental  self  in  the 
Kantian  terminology,  which  is  aware  of  these  experiences, 
to  whom  these  experiences,  in  some  sense,  belong.  The 
structure  of  the  empirical  self  is  usually  represented  as  dis 
crete.  As  Hume  expressed  it  in  the  oft-quoted  passage,  it  is 
"nothing  but  a  bundle  or  collection  of  different  perceptions, 
which  succeed  each  other  with  an  inconceivable  rapidity, 
and  are  in  a  perpetual  flux  and  movement."  This  view  of 
the  empirical  self  is  of  the  largest  historical  importance,  since 
it  forms  the  presupposition  of  nearly  all  the  discussion  of  the 
self  since  Hume's  day.  Writers  have  either  regarded  the 
self's  contents  as  permanently  discrete,  with  all  the  conse 
quences  which  this  view  entails,  or  else  have  expended  their 
efforts  in  devising  something  to  provide  the  systematic  con 
nection  within  the  self  which  was  originally  lacking,  to  weld, 
as  it  were,  the  sundered  elements  of  experience  and  make 
out  of  them  a  rational  whole. 

The  discussion  since  Hume  has  largely  centered  around 
the  question  of  the  transcendental  self,  around  the  question 
whether  the  existence  of  the  self  as  knower,  understood  to 
be  a  permanent  entity  of  some  sort,  other  than  any  transitory 
process  or  content  within  the  conscious  stream  itself,  is 
scientifically  defensible.  It  is  at  this  point  that  a  funda 
mental  divergence  of  opinion  as  to  the  methods  which  are 
fruitful  in  such  discussions  has  made  itself  most  severely  felt, 
and  a  difference  of  findings  is  probably  inevitable  so  long 
as  no  initial  agreement  on  methodological  principles  exists. 
One  group  of  writers,  following  Hume,  recognizes  only  the 
immediately  given;  their  appeal  is  to  *  facts'  revealed  to  ob 
servation,  which  are  to  be  described  and  explained,  all  ex 
planation,  in  turn,  being  in  terms  of  the  conscious  stream 
itself.  Another  group  of  writers  is  convinced  that  the 


280  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

experiences  immediately  given  find  their  adequate  explana 
tion  only  in  entities  or  principles  which  lie  outside  immediate 
experience,  entities  which  can  be  reached  only  by  a  process 
of  logical  inference.  That  anything  more  than  an  advance 
in  the  solution  of  the  problem  under  discussion  is  to  be  ex 
pected,  even  if  the  disputants  could  be  forced  to  some  com 
mon  methodological  basis,  is  probably  too  much  to  hope,  in 
view  of  the  fact  that,  even  where  such  a  common  basis  ap 
pears  to  exist,  serious  differences  of  opinion  remain.  The 
fact  is,  that,  so  far  from  finding  agreement  in  results  among 
those  holding  similar  methodological  points  of  view,  we  find 
four  distinct  positions  maintained  by  writers  of  standing. 
There  are  those  who  recognize  the  self  as  a  permanent  entity, 
existing  over  and  above  the  discrete  ideas  and  functions 
which  are  said  to  compose  the  stream  of  consciousness,  as 
an  object  of  immediate  experience  (Calkins) ;  1  another  group 
of  writers  disclaims  an  immediate  experience  of  such  an  en 
tity,  and  does  not  regard  extra-psychological  considerations 
as  admissible  in  the  discussion  (Titchener) ;  a  third  class  of 
writers  agrees  that  a  separate  self  fitting  the  traditional  de 
scription  of  the  transcendental  self  is  logically  implied  by 
the  facts  of  experience,  or  is  required  as  an  explanatory 
principle  (the  Neo-Kantians) ;  and,  finally,  there  is  a  fourth 
class  of  writers  who,  although  admitting  the  scientific  status 
of  entities  logically  implied  by  the  data  of  immediate  ex 
perience,  or  required  for  their  explanation,  do  not  recognize 
the  logical  necessity  of  postulating  the  self's  existence  (James, 
Pillsbury). 

I  shall  set  down,  in  what  follows,  with  as  much  support  as 
the  limits  of  my  space  permit,  a  few  points  which,  while  in  no 
sense  new,  may  prove  useful  in  dealing  with  the  self- 
problem. 

It  seems  to  me  an  indefensible  position,  in  the  first  place, 
to  suggest  that  psychology  is,  or  must  be,  presuppositionless, 
and  that  it  cannot,  as  a  science,  admit  the  existence  of  any 

1  This  seems  to  be  the  position  of  Professor  Calkins,  but  I  am  not  at 
all  confident  that  I  understand  her  view  of  the  relation  of  the  self  to  the 
empirical  data  of  consciousness. 


SELFHOOD  281 

entities  which  do  not  come  in  the  guise  of  presented  facts, 
but  are  merely  explanatory  postulates  suggested  by  the  pre 
sented  facts.  If  this  is  really  the  case,  psychology  stands 
alone  among  the  sciences  in  this  regard.  The  method  of 
science,  as  of  philosophy,  it  seems  to  me,  must  be  experience 
and  legitimate  inference  from  experience;  and  I  do  not  think 
that  it  would  be  difficult  to  show  that  every  psychologist,  no 
matter  to  what  tendency  in  psychology  he  adheres,  recognizes 
and  employs  logical  constructions  of  various  types  for  which 
only  the  suggestions  are  contained  in  the  empirical  materials 
with  which  he  works.  The  real,  as  Dr.  Bosanquet  somewhere 
says,  is  what  we  are  obliged  to  think,  and  the  knowledge  of 
reality  which  science  affords  would  be  immeasurably  im 
poverished  if  the  hypothetical  and  logical  elements  which  it 
contains  were  eliminated  from  it.  If  the  separate  self,  there 
fore,  were  clearly  required  by  the  facts  of  psychology,  I  do 
not  see  why  the  self  should  not  be  admitted  for  what  it  is: 
not  as  an  experienced  fact,  as  a  datum  on  the  same  plane 
with  Hume's  impressions,  but  as  an  explanatory  principle 
without  which  the  observed  facts  of  consciousness  would  be 
unintelligible.  Its  justification  would  be  pragmatic:  it  would 
be  justified  by  its  success  in  explaining  characteristics  of  ex 
perience  which  would  remain  unintelligible  without  its  as 
sumption. 

Nevertheless,  it  would  be  clearly  needless  to  treat  the  per 
manent  self  as  a  logical  construction,  if  it  proved  to  be  an 
empirical  datum.  That  it  is  such  a  datum  is  asserted  by 
Professor  Calkins,  for  example,  according  to  whom  the  self 
is  not  only  immediately  known  to  exist,  but  is  immediately 
experienced  "as  persistent,  inclusive,  unique,  and  related." 
Only  as  immediately  experienced,  she  adds,  have  we  a  right 
to  use  these  characteristics  in  describing  consciousness.1 

It  seems  pertinent  to  inquire  whether  such  characters  as 
are  here  enumerated  can  be  data  of  immediate  experience 
at  all.  To  the  present  writer  it  seems  as  improbable  that 

1  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific  Methods,  Vol.  V,  1908, 
pp.  64-68.  See  also  the  same  author's  A  First  Book  in  Psychology,  p.  3, 
and  elsewhere. 


282  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

these  characters  can  be  given  in  immediate  experience  as 
that  Hume's  bundle  of  perceptions  should  be  a  datum  of 
immediate  experience.  The  characteristics  which  Professor 
Calkins  ascribes  to  the  self,  as  well  as  those  which  Hume 
ascribes  to  it,  imply  a  knowledge  of  the  self  in  its  entirety, 
in  some  sense;  but  the  history  of  the  self  as  a  whole  cannot 
possibly  be  an  object  of  immediate  experience.1 

In  other  passages  of  Professor  Calkins's  account,  however, 
the  term  self  does  not  seem  clearly  to  stand  for  a  separate 
self,  or  for  a  type  of  activity,  as  it  does  in  Kant;  it  appears 
rather  as  a  generic  term,  denoting  a  "complex  of  ideas,  func 
tions,  experiences."  How  one  is  to  reconcile  the  trait  of 
"inclusiveness,"  in  the  sense  just  defined,  with  the  trait  of 
"uniqueness,"  as  next  described  by  Professor  Calkins,  is  not 
easy  to  see.  When  we  "reflect  upon"  the  self  (is  'reflect 
upon'  the  word?),  "we  may  describe  it  as  a  consciousness  of 
a  this-which-could-not-be-replaced-by-another.  Now  we 
simply  are  not  conscious  of  ideas  and  functions  as,  in  this 
sense,  unique.  A  given  self,  with  a  different  idea,  is  still  this 
self,"  etc.2  How  a  self  can  gain  and  pay  off  ideas  indefinitely 
and  itself  remain  unperturbed  and  unaltered  in  its  essence  is 
perhaps  a  problem  for  those  versed  in  the  ways  of  the 
Absolute.  That  the  empirical  self  should  be  able  to  maintain 
a  consciousness  of  self-identity  after  a  partial  alteration  of 
its  contents,  owing  to  the  loss  of  some  elements  and  the 
acquisition  of  new  ones,  is,  however,  not  in  the  least  sur 
prising,  when  one  remembers  the  enormous  scope  of  the  self's 
history  and  the  comparative  unimportance,  therefore,  of 
the  changes  wrought  in  it  by  any  passing  experience.  The 
fact  that  the  consciousness  of  self-identity  does  actually 
become  uncertain  when  the  changes  in  its  experience  are 
sufficiently  radical  and  abrupt,  or  when  they  affect  its  more 

1  This  is  a  fact  which,  when  clearly  recognized,  is  seen  to  invalidate 
either  Hume's  theory  of  the  self,  as  set  out  in  his  famous  definition,  or 
else  his  theory  that  the  only  valid  knowledge  is  that  which  originates  in 
impressions. 

2  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific  Methods,  Vol.  V, 
1908,  p.  66. 


SELFHOOD  283 

characteristic  phases,  as  in  the  more  serious  perversions  of 
bodily  sensibility,  is,  I  believe,  not  without  significance  for 
our  problem.  Whatever  our  decision  on  this  may  be,  we 
are  safe  in  asserting  that  a  self  which  persisted  unchanged 
and  unique  in  spite  of  its  changing  ideas,  functions,  and  ex 
periences,  if  such  a  self  indeed  existed,  could  not  possibly  be 
an  object  of  immediate  experience.  The  self,  whether  re 
garded  as  a  name  for  the  conscious  life-history  of  the  in 
dividual  or  as  an  entity  or  function  outside  of  and  separate 
from  the  stream  of  individual  experience,  is  surely  an  ideal 
construction,  a  conceptual  generalization  of  which  the  im 
mediately  given  experience  forms  merely  the  nucleus  or  core. 
By  self-consciousness,  I  conclude,  we  mean,  or  ought  to 
mean,  merely  the  felt  togetherness,  the  continuity,  of  any 
present  experience  with  the  other  constituents  of  the  con 
scious  stream.  Interpreted  in  this  sense,  James's  assertion 
of  personal  selfhood  possesses  absolute  validity.  "  It  seems 
as  if  the  elementary  psychic  fact  is  not  thought  or  this  thought 
or  that  thought,  but  my  thought,  every  thought  being 
owned.  .  .  .  Every  one  will  recognise  this  to  be  true,  so 
long  as  the  existence  of  something  corresponding  to  the  term 
'personal  mind'  is  all  that  is  insisted  on,  without  any  par 
ticular  view  of  its  nature  being  implied.  On  these  terms  the 
personal  self  rather  than  the  thought  might  be  treated  as 
the  immediate  datum  in  psychology.  .  .  .  Thoughts  con 
nected  as  we  feel  them  to  be  connected  is  what  we  mean 
by  personal  selves."  l  Of  the  existence  of  the  self,  thus 
interpreted,  there  cannot  be  the  slightest  doubt.  In  the 
writer's  own  introspection,  the  focal  elements  of  conscious 
ness  are  merely  emphasised  phases  of  a  more  or  less  distinct 
background  of  marginal  experiences,  of  which  the  feeling  of 
the  body  is  by  far  the  most  frequently  recurring  constant 
feature,  although  this  may,  in  moments  of  higher  attentive 
concentration,  entirely  disappear.  In  addition,  there  is  a 
large  field  of  other  marginal  constituents,  of  which  the  ideal 
associations  and  meanings  clustering  around  the  more 
prominent-appearing  perceptual  and  imaginal  structures 
1  Psychology:  Briefer  Course,  p.  153. 


284  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

form  ever-present,  though  constantly  shifting,  features.  In 
the  empirical  sense  here  explained,  consciousness  and  self- 
consciousness,  indeed,  turn  out  to  be  indistinguishable  terms. 
They  are  as  correlative  as  perception  and  apperception,  fore 
ground  and  background,  focus  and  margin.  Our  answer, 
then,  to  the  question  what  the  self  is,  would  be  that  it  is  a 
name  for  the  experiences  of  the  individual  felt  and  reflectively 
conceived  as  forming  in  some  sense  a  unity  or  system;  it  is 
the  stream  of  consciousness  itself,  viewed  as  coherent  and 
continuous.  If  an  answer  were  demanded  as  to  some  specific 
or  permanent  structure  within  the  conscious  stream  which  is 
the  self,  I  should  reply  (although  reluctantly),  the  body.1 

It  is  the  recognition  of  the  continuity  and  coherence  of 
mental  states,  just  referred  to,  however,  that  offers  the  self- 
psychologist  of  the  traditional  Kantian  type  the  cue  for  his 
crowning  argument.  The  native  stuff  of  consciousness,  it  is 
said  (with  what  warrant  does  not  always  appear),  is  a  chaotic 
manifold.  Now  it  is  the  function  of  the  self  to  remove  the 
heterogeneity,  to  overcome  the  discreteness,  which  primordial 
experience  presents.  This  is  indeed  the  fundamental  view 
of  Kant,  according  to  whom  the  Durcheinander,  the  natural 
chaos  of  sense  experience,  is  ordered  and  organized  through 
the  synthetic  activity  of  intelligence.  "Die  Verbindung 
eines  Mannigfaltigen,"  he  wrote,  "kann  iiberhaupt  niemals 
durch  die  Sinne  in  uns  kommen.  .  .  .  Alle  Verbindung  ist 
eine  Verstandeshandlung."  What  is  true  of  the  raw  ma 
terial  of  sense  is  true  of  ideas  as  well.  Each  idea,  too,  is 
distinct  from  every  other,  and  the  recognition  of  relations, 
of  whatever  type,  among  ideas  implies  the  self  as  a  relating 
principle  or  agent.  This  view,  thoroughly  domesticated  in 
English  philosophy  mainly  through  the  influence  of  Green, 
is  typically  expressed  in  a  passage  of  Lotze's  Metaphysic: 
"Any  comparison  of  two  ideas,  which  ends  by  our  finding 

1  If  the  organic  connection  between  any  given  mental  content  and  the 
rest  of  personal  consciousness  to  which  it  belongs  is  definitely  recognized, 
the  objections  often  urged  against  writers,  that  they  employ  terms  imply 
ing  the  existence  of  the  self  when  they  deny  its  existence,  are  seen  to  be 
groundless. 


SELFHOOD  285 

their  contents  like  or  unlike,  presupposes  the  absolutely  in 
divisible  unity  of  that  which  compares  them;  it  must  be  one 
and  the  same  thing  which  first  forms  the  idea  of  #,  then  that 
of  by  and  which  at  the  same  time  is  conscious  of  the  nature 
and  extent  of  the  difference  between  them.  .  .  .  And  so 
our  whole  inner  world  of  thoughts  is  built  up;  not  as  a  mere 
collection  of  manifold  ideas  existing  with  or  after  one  an 
other,  but  as  a  world  in  which  these  individual  members  are 
held  together  and  arranged  by  the  relating  activity  of  this 
single  pervading  principle.  This  then  is  what  we  mean  by 
the  unity  of  consciousness;  and  it  is  this  that  we  regard  as 
the  sufficient  ground  for  assuming  an  indivisible  soul."  1 

Without  delaying  to  discuss  the  now  partly  obsolete  con 
ception  of  Kant,  that  primitive  experience  consists  of  isolated, 
uncompounded  elements  which  are  united  into  wholes  by  a 
subsequent  process  of  mental  synthesis,  it  is  perhaps  suffi 
cient  to  point  out  that,  in  order  for  the  relations  between 
different  contents  to  appear,  it  is  only  necessary  that  these 
contents  should  be  assembled  into  larger  units  of  conscious 
ness  in  which  the  contents  in  question,  together  with  the 
relations  appearing  between  them,  will  be  comprehended. 
If  the  objection  is  raised  that  the  formation  of  such  larger 
units  would  not  provide  for  the  permanence  of  the  self,  the 
reply  is  that  this  does  not  necessarily  follow  and  that  the 
objection  is,  in  any  case,  irrelevant,  since  the  permanence  of 
the  self  is  one  of  the  questions  at  issue.  The  permanence  of 
the  self,  argued  from  its  synthetic  function,  would  under  any 
view  be  no  greater  than  the  range  of  the  objects  which  it 
synthesizes;  that  is,  it  would  be  finite  and  variable.  A 
similar  statement  would  apply  to  the  alleged  unity  of  the 
self  asserted  to  be  implied  by  its  unifying  function.  Here  too 
we  reply  that  its  unity  would  be  merely  as  great  as,  but  no 
greater  than,  the  unity  belonging  to  its  objects.  But  its 
objects  always  fail  of  being  perfectly  systematic.  The  finite 
self's  world  (whatever  might  be  said  of  the  Absolute's)  is 
always  in  part  incoherent. 

If,  then,  the  question  is  asked,  Who  is  the  knower?  What 
1  Tr.  edited  by  Bosanquet,  2d  edition,  Vol.  II,  pp.  i/of. 


286  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

is  it  that  apprehends  relations  between  the  parts  of  a  mani 
fold?  perhaps  the  best  reply  that  can  be  given  is  in  the  tradi 
tional  terms:  It  is  the  mind  or  the  self.  Only  by  the  self 
is  not  now  meant  some  non-empirical  principle,  forever 
identical  with  itself,  existing  over  and  above  the  stream  of 
consciousness,  but  the  concrete  stream  of  consciousness 
itself.  Not  only  is  the  self  as  thus  understood  the  knower;  it 
is  the  agent  in  every  other  mental  operation  as  well.  The 
self,  as  Professor  Pillsbury  has  well  put  it,  "is  all  that  we 
are  and  know,  organized,  self-unified,  and  self-identical,  a 
growing  vital  unity  that  as  a  whole  is  effective  in  every 
experience.  When  it  is  directed  towards  the  control  of  ac 
tion,  we  know  it  as  will;  when  choosing  from  the  many 
stimuli  that  offer,  as  attention;  when  interpreting  the 
stimulus,  as  perception  or  judgment;  when  constructing  new 
forms  from  old  experiences,  as  reason.  But  it  is  the  same 
everywhere,  always  active,  and  active  in  very  much  the 
same  way  in  every  kind  of  mental  process."  1  That  such  an 
empirical  knower  is,  from  a  scientific  point  of  view,  incom 
parably  preferable  to  the  hypothetical  self  of  traditional 
metaphysics  goes  without  saying,  since  the  problem  of  ex 
plaining  how  the  synthesis  of  a  manifold  is  effected  is  by  no 
means  lightened,  but  only  aggravated,  by  invoking  a  unitary 
substance  placed  outside  the  stream  of  consciousness,  and 
hence  beyond  the  reach  of  empirical  observation.  "The 
idea  of  a  self  or  Ego,"  as  Mr.  Bradley  says,  "joining  together 
from  the  outside  the  atomic  elements,  and  fastening  them 
together  in  some  miraculous  way,  not  involved  in  their  own 
nature,  is  quite  indefensible.  It  would  be  the  addition  of 
one  more  discrete  to  the  former  chaos  of  discretes,  and  it 
would  still  leave  them  all  discrete.  The  idea  of  anything 
being  made  wholly  from  the  outside  into  something  else  .  .  . 
seems  in  short  utterly  irrational." 

Whether  the  stream  of  consciousness  itself  is  capable  of 
bearing  the  burden  placed  upon  it  is  a  question  which  cannot 
be  answered  by  mere  assertion,  but  only  by  actually  demon- 

1  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XVI,  1907,  p.  406. 

2  Mind,  N.  S.,  Vol.  IX,  1900,  p.  37. 


SELFHOOD  287 

strating  this  possibility  in  connection  with  the  various  mental 
functions  in  turn.  The  illustrations  of  the  success  of  psy 
chology  in  the  explanation  of  the  mind's  various  functions 
without  the  hypothesis  of  the  traditional  self  are  found  in 
abundance  in  every  modern  psychological  text-book.  Not 
only  in  the  literal  reinstatements  of  memory,  where  the  past 
history  of  the  individual's  consciousness  is  of  course  of  prime 
importance,  but  in  the  more  selective  functions  of  attention, 
perception,  association,  conception,  reasoning,  emotion,  and 
action,  the  controlling  influence  of  experience  as  a  whole  is 
being  demonstrated  with  a  constantly  increasing  complete 
ness  and  detail.  Mental  functions  formerly  assigned  to  a 
set  of  mythical  faculties  or  to  a  discarnate  soul  are  seen  to 
be  the  activities  or  effects  of  systems  of  earlier  experience 
which  project  themselves  into  the  present,  determining  the 
further  developments  of  experience  at  every  step.1  The 
completion  of  this  work  of  retrospective  explanation  must,  of 
course,  be  viewed  as  a  scientific  aspiration  rather  than  as  a 
humanly  possible  achievement.  Nor  can  the  assertion  of 
Professor  Pillsbury,  that  no  part  of  past  experience  is  ever 
lost  or  is  without  a  determining  influence  upon  present  con 
sciousness  or  behavior,  be  viewed  as  anything  more  than  an 
hypothesis,  the  truth  of  which  lies  wholly  beyond  the  pos 
sibility  of  scientific  determination. 

A  type  of  explanation  of  the  self's  unity,  to  which  prom 
inence  has  often  been  given,  is  by  reference  to  the  existence 
within  the  self  of  characteristic  interests  and  purposes  which 
remain  relatively  permanent  throughout  the  various  muta 
tions  which  the  self  otherwise  suffers.  According  to  this  view, 
the  unity  of  the  self  is  a  teleological  unity,  like  that  of  a 
drama  or  a  game  of  skill,  a  unity  imparted  to  it  by  an  under 
lying  plan,  aim,  or  interest  which  the  self  is  striving  to  realise 
or  fulfill.  The  two  types  of  explanation,  although  appearing 
at  first  sight  to  involve  different  principles,  are  related  to 
each  other  as  causal  and  teleological  explanation  in  general. 
They  are  hence  not  contradictory  but  supplementary. 

1  For  a  brief  summary  of  the  progress  of  recent  psychology  in  empirical 
explanations  of  this  sort,  see  Pillsbury,  loc.  cit.,  especially  pp.  393-400. 


288  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

Nevertheless,  it  must  be  recognized  that,  owing  to  the  feeble 
operation  of  the  conative  tendencies  represented  by  the  self's 
current  aims  and  interests,  the  organization  and  integration 
of  the  inner  life  remains  always  at  any  given  time  imperfect, 
to  say  nothing  of  the  fluctuations  of  the  interests  and  ideals 
themselves,  incident  to  maturation  and  decline,  and  to  the 
various  crises  to  which  the  inner  life  is  always  exposed.  Not 
only  is  there  at  any  given  time  a  more  or  less  permanent 
stratification  of  the  self  into  systems  of  different  and  more 
or  less  incompatible  interests  and  aims,  but  the  history  of 
any  life  is  often  little  more  than  a  succession  of  different 
groups  of  interests  and  aims,  each  of  which  arises  only  to 
dissolve  and  give  way  to  its  successors.  It  may  thus  easily 
happen  that  two  stages  of  a  man's  life,  removed  from  each 
other  by  considerable  periods  of  time,  resemble  each  other 
less  than  two  parallel  stages  of  different  men's  lives,  so  that 
individual  identity  would  here  evidently  be  little  more  than 
a  name.  The  actually  verifiable  identity  of  the  self,  we  con 
clude,  no  matter  from  what  view  it  is  regarded,  is  a  partial 
and  variable,  not  an  absolute,  quantity,  which  belongs  to  it 
in  its  own  right. 

A  word  might  be  said  in  conclusion  about  the  bearing  of  our 
results  on  the  question  of  the  survival  of  the  self  after  the 
disappearance  of  the  body,  upon  the  relation  to  which,  as 
we  have  seen,  its  self-identity  so  largely  depends.  But  I  do 
not  wish  to  go  into  the  question  here,  since  I  have  dealt  with 
it  somewhat  fully  elsewhere,1  beyond  the  statement  that 
the  self's  survival,  in  so  far  as  it  does  indeed  survive  the  body, 
will  probably  depend  upon  the  extent  to  which  it  has  achieved 
unity  of  life  through  the  consistent  pursuit  of  some  aim, 
interest,  or  plan,  and  upon  the  degree  to  which  this  aim, 
interest,  or  plan  coincides  with  the  fundamental  purpose  of 
the  universe  in  which  the  self  is  to  exist.  Even  this  belief, 

1  The  Problem  of  Religion,  Ch.  VI,  and  Henri  Bergson,  Ch.  XVII.  There 
is  a  particularly  valuable  discussion  of  the  self  and  its  place  in  reality  as  a 
whole  in  Professor  A.  E.  Taylor's  Elements  of  Metaphysics,  from  which  I 
have  received  important  suggestions,  although  I  find  myself  dissenting 
on  some  points. 


SELFHOOD  289 

it  is  seen,  implies  a  conception  of  the  universe  which  must 
probably  be  viewed  as  an  object  of  faith  and  hope,  rather 
than  of  logical  demonstration.  Nothing  finer  has  been  said 
upon  this  than  by  Lotze:  We  have  no  other  principle  for 
deciding  the  probability  of  immortality  "beyond  this  gen 
eral  idealistic  conviction,  that  every  created  thing  will  con 
tinue,  if  and  so  long  as  its  continuance  belongs  to  the  meaning 
of  the  world;  that  everything  will  pass  away  which  had  its 
authorised  place  only  in  a  transitory  phase  of  the  world's 
course.  That  this  principle  admits  of  no  further  application 
in  human  hands  hardly  needs  to  be  mentioned.  We  certainly 
do  not  know  the  merits  which  may  give  to  one  existence  a 
claim  to  eternity,  nor  the  defects  which  deny  it  to  others."  l 

1  Metaphysic,  tr.  edited  by  Bosanquet,  Vol.  II,  p.  182. 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT 

ROBERT  MORRIS  OGDEN 

THERE  exists  at  the  present  time  a  wide  range  of  opinion 
concerning  psychology  as  a  science:  its  aims,  its  point  of 
view,  its  fundamental  principles,  and  its  methodology.  On 
one  hand,  we  have  structuralists  holding  more  or  less  con 
sistently  to  the  description  and  analysis  of  conscious  con 
tents.  In  order  to  explain  the  conscious  continuum,  a  sort 
of  psychical  linkage  between  contents  is  assumed.  This 
linkage  is  usually  referred  to  underlying  physiological  proc 
esses  in  the  nervous  system.  These  nervous  processes  may 
then  be  conceived  as  affording  the  only  real  basis  for  a  causal 
interpretation  of  mind.  Some,  however,  lay  stress  upon 
associative  linkage  within  consciousness,  even  leaning  to 
wards  a  conception  of  psychical  causality  distinct  from, 
though  possibly  still  paralleling,  the  physical  causality  of 
nervous  processes.  Among  the  more  extreme  structuralists 
we  find  a  tacit  renunciation  of  the  problems  of  behavior,  of 
learning,  of  meaningful  interpretation,  and  the  like.  The 
contents  of  consciousness  which  appear  in  such  functions 
are  described  for  themselves  alone,  while  the  function  itself 
is  relegated  to  the  sphere  of  the  ' practical'  and  non-scientific. 

In  some  sense  as  a  reaction  against  the  limitations  set  by 
a  'pure'  psychology  which  makes  the  definition  of  conscious 
structures  its  chief  or  only  concern,  we  have  the  program  of 
the  behaviorist.  Realizing  that  the  practical  problems  must 
be  solved,  the  behaviorist  has  proposed  a  solution  in  ob 
jective  terms.  These  terms  are  nervous  processes  in  causal 
sequence.  The  behaviorist  starts  from  the  general  assump 
tion  of  nervous  connections  mediating  between  external 
situations  (stimuli)  and  internal  responses  (mainly  muscular 
and  glandular).  His  aim,  then,  is  to  understand  the  nature 
of  these  connections  as  laid  down  in  the  nervous  system  at 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT  291 

birth,  and  as  modified  through  subsequent  training,  by 
establishing  the  causal  connection  between  situations  and 
responses,  each  of  which  can  be  directly  analyzed  and  its 
effective  nature  determined. 

The  limitations  which  are  self-imposed  alike  in  the  doc 
trines  of  the  structuralist  and  of  the  behaviorist  indicate 
both  the  strength  and  weakness  of  these  respective  views. 
It  is  not  undesirable  that  one  should  concern  himself  with 
the  purely  existential  in  consciousness,  in  order  that  he  may 
push  his  analysis  to  its  furthermost  bounds  without  ulterior 
considerations.  Neither  is  it  undesirable  that  one  should 
attempt  a  study  of  behavior  in  terms  of  nervous  processes 
and  connections  that  are  purely  objective.  But  to  those 
who  are  interested  in  the  question:  What  is  mind  for? 
neither  the  structuralist  nor  the  behaviorist  gives  a  satis 
factory  answer.  The  former  does  not  raise  the  question  of 
behavior,  while  the  latter,  making  it  his  chief  concern,  neg 
lects  conscious  participation  as  in  no  wise  relevant  to  his 
problem.  Each  rejects  a  functional  interpretation  of  mind, 
although  it  is  only  by  functioning  that  mind  can  possibly 
be  of  use. 

It  is  with  some  of  the  more  general  aspects  of  functional 
psychology  that  we  are  concerned  in  this  paper.  The  point 
of  view  from  which  the  problem  is  treated  is  mainly  that  of 
the  so-called  "  Wiirzburg  School."  As  a  result  of  the  contro 
versy  which  arose  regarding  the  existence  of  imageless  con 
tents,  the  main  trend  of  the  investigations  of  the  thought- 
processes  directed  by  the  late  Professor  Oswald  Kulpe  has 
been  somewhat  obscured.  From  personal  conversations  with 
Kiilpe,  I  gathered  that  his  chief  object  was  to  determine  the 
significance  and  variety  of  mental  acts  and  functions.  Un 
fortunately,  his  career  was  closed  before  the  experimental 
foundations  of  such  a  program  had  been  completely  laid. 
Among  the  products  of  his  laboratory,  the  investigation  of 
Ernst  Westphal,  "Uber  Haupt-  und  Nebenaufgaben  bei 
Reaktionsversuche,"  1  is  perhaps  the  most  important  con 
tribution  to  this  particular  end.  Special  reference  to  this 
1  Arch.},  d.  ges.  PsychoL,  Vol.  XXI,  1911,  pp.  219-434. 


292  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

work  is  made  here  because  the  doctrine  of  the  "stages  of 
consciousness"  which  Westphal  developed  has  furnished  the 
point  of  departure  for  our  general  theory  of  mental  activity 
and  conscious  content. 

Taking  as  his  problem  the  primary  and  secondary  tasks 
which  any  situation  is  likely  to  suggest,  Westphal  set  about 
to  determine  the  nature  and  interplay  of  such  functions. 
As  material  he  drew  a  variety  of  polygons  on  cards.  These 
were  exposed  with  the  aid  of  a  card-changer,  and  the  observer 
was  instructed  to  determine  the  number  of  angles  and  the 
longest  side.  These  determinations  served,  now  the  one, 
now  the  other,  as  his  primary  and  secondary  tasks. 

From  the  introspective  reports  of  his  observers,  Westphal 
was  able  to  differentiate  the  following  five  "stages"  in  the 
solutions  of  his  problems : 

1.  The  result  is  merely  given  in  consciousness.    This  means 
that  the  object  representing  the  solution  of  the  problem,  as 
for  instance  the  contour  of  the  figure,  is  seen  in  a  clear  and 
definite  manner.    Yet  it  is  only  seen.    No  conscious  relations 
are  established,  for  the  particular  point  of  view  of  the  task 
is  not  brought  to  bear  consciously  upon  the  object.     The 
observer  reports  that  "nothing  was  done  with  it;"  "it  was 
not  evaluated;"  "no  notice  was  taken  of  it,"  and  the  like. 

2.  The  object  is  noted  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  task. 
Nothing  is  altered  in  the  content.    The  object  is  not  clearer, 
at  least  not  necessarily  so,  yet  the  point  of  view  afforded  by 
the  task  is  now  directed  upon  it.     While  the  contour  was 
previously  quite  definite,  it  is  now  noted  to  be  straight  or 
curved;  it  is  seen  as  straight  or  curved. 

3.  The  object  is  potentially  known,  though  still  unformu- 
lated  and  unexpressed.    When  the  task  is  not  too  difficult, 
the  stage  of  noting  leads  immediately  to  a  potential  knowl 
edge  of  the  result.    That  is,  if  the  contour  of  the  figure  has 
been  noted  as  curved,  the  observer  now  knows  that  it  is 
curved,  without,  however,  being  expressly  confronted  with 
his  knowledge.     If  a  decision  was  to  be  reached  between  a 
triangle  and  a  square,  the  observer  knows  what  kind  of 
figure  it  is  without  an  expressed  knowledge  of  the  number  of 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT  293 

sides  or  angles.  He  knows  without  naming.  He  has  a  kind 
of  knowledge  of  three-sidedness  or  four-sidedness,  but  it  is 
unformulated  in  his  mind.  It  is  not  an  actual  but  a  potential 
knowledge.  When  the  task  is  too  difficult,  noting  does  not 
always  suffice  for  potential  knowledge  of  the  result;  the 
formulation  must  be  completed  by  another  step  which  may 
rest  directly  upon  noting,  without  the  mediation  of  a  stage 
which  can  be  termed  potential  knowledge. 

4.  The  object  is  known  and  formulated  (konstatiert) .    The 
observer  experiences  here  an  expressed  knowledge  of  his 
result.     The  contour  of  the  figure  is  determined  as  curved 
rather  than  as  straight.     The  sides  which  have  been  seen 
are  determined  as  being  curved  sides.     Words  are  not  an 
essential  part  of  this  formulation,  yet  they  are  usually  in 
readiness  for  its  expression.    The  definite  act  of  establishment 
is  the  important  factor,  though  it  is  somewhat  difficult  to 
describe.    The  observer  refers  to  it  as  the  act  of  "establish 
ing,"  "determining,"  "nailing  fast,"  etc. 

5.  There  is  also  a  lower  stage  than  the  first  mentioned, 
at  which  the  result  is  in  no  sense  achieved,  yet  data  are 
given   from  which  it  may  be   subsequently  obtained   (er- 
schliessbar).     This  is  inferred  from  later  reproductions  and 
conclusions,  which  appear  to  require  that  a  characteristic 
right  angle,  or  some  other  detail,  has  been  presented,  in  order 
to  justify  the  judgment  now  reached. 

It  will  be  seen  that  these  distinctions  bear  closely  upon  the 
special  problem  of  WestphaPs  investigation.  Although  they 
have  a  wide  range  of  application,  as  the  author  has  clearly 
pointed  out,  they  are  not  inclusive  enough  to  afford  a  com 
plete  survey  of  mental  functions,  since  they  are  limited  to 
the  genesis  of  a  special  problem-consciousness.  The  scope 
of  the  mind's  activity  must  be  wider  than  this,  if  only  to 
afford  the  presentations  upon  which  the  problem-conscious 
ness  may  operate.  Accordingly,  we  shall  suggest  a  revision 
of  Westphal's  doctrine  to  embrace  the  following  three  stages : 
(i)  Simple  Presentation,  (2)  Awareness,  (3)  Cognition. 

The  first  of  these  stages  is  analogous  to  Westphal's  fifth, 
or  lowest,  stage;  yet  it  is  not  identical  with  it.  The  erschliess- 


294  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

bar  stage  embraces  data  which,  though  not  acted  upon 
at  the  time,  are  nevertheless  selected  for  later  activity  be 
cause  of  their  relevancy  to  the  problem  at  hand.  The  data 
are  relevant  data,  though  their  relevancy  is  not  at  the  time 
cfelt.'  The  stage  of  Simple  Presentation  may  embrace  such 
objectively  relevant  contents,  but  it  also  includes  others 
having  no  connection  with  the  task.  These  others  may  be 
present  simply  because  the  sense  receptors  have  been  ap 
propriately  stimulated,  or  because  the  associative  mechanism 
has  been  operative. 

The  definition  of  presentation  here  adopted  is  nearly  that 
of  Stout  when  he  designates  the  objective  facts  of  "imme 
diate  experience"  by  this  term.1  But  when  Stout  refers  to 
the  function  of  presentations  "present  objects  which  are  not 
themselves  presentations,"  2  and  upon  this  elaborates  a 
doctrine  of  the  direction  of  thought,  our  agreement  is  only 
partial.  According  to  our  view,  presentations  as  such  do 
not  function  at  all.  Association  is  the  chief  function  which 
may  be  operative  at  this  stage.  No  other  functioning  is 
implied,  though  another  is  possible,  as  we  shall  see  later.  An 
object  when  presented  opens  the  way  for  others  not  presented, 
through  its  associative  connections  with  them.  Previously 
formed  associations  make  possible  readiness  for  revival.  The 
formation  of  new  associations  at  the  stage  of  Simple  Pres 
entation  is  also  probable,  though  some  investigators  have 
concluded  that  attention  is  a  necessary  factor.  We  need 
not  concern  ourselves  here  with  this  question,  except  to 
remark  that  many  of  the  mental  acts  commonly  attributed 
to  the  'unconscious  mind'  seem  at  least  to  demand  the 
formation  of  new  associations,  if  not  a  more  rational  type 
of  functioning.  Therefore,  these  acts  may  occur  without 
conscious  awareness. 

The  stage  of  Simple  Presentation  affords  a  wealth  of 
sensory,  imaginal,  notional,  and  affective  material,  and  a 
diversity  of  associative  connections.  It  is  in  a  sense  hy 
pothetical,  because  it  is  not  directly  subject  to  observation. 
At  this  level  a  strict  differentiation  of  the  physiological  and 

1  Manual  of  Psychology,  3d  ed.,  1913,  p.  n.  2  Ibid.,  p.  171. 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT  295 

the  psychological  is  impossible.  All  we  can  know  of  it  is 
known  indirectly.  We  assume  that  the  bit  of  color  now 
clearly  within  our  range  of  vision  was  there  somehow  before 
we  noted  its  presence,  but  whether  its  thereness  was  physical, 
physiological,  or  psychological  is  a  matter  of  hypothesis. 
Later  revival,  and  modifications  of  behavior  that  can  be 
traced  to  such  a  source,  justify  the  assumption  of  actuality 
for  these  contents  in  simple  presentation  as  mental,  though 
not  necessarily  as  conscious  facts. 

The  second  stage  of  consciousness,  which  we  have  called 
the  stage  of  Awareness,  is  effected  by  the  action  of  attention. 
Attention,  as  here  defined,  has  the  single  function  of  clarify 
ing  the  contents  upon  which  it  acts.  It  is  important  to  note 
this  limitation  upon  the  function  of  attention.  The  term 
has  a  number  of  meanings.  It  is  frequently  used  in  so  broad 
a  manner  that  it  may  embrace  awareness  of  momentary  and 
irrelevant  distractions  at  one  extreme  and  concentrated 
thought  at  the  other.  In  the  interests  of  greater  precision  in 
the  characterization  of  mental  activities,  we  have  purposely 
renounced  all  but  the  narrow  function  of  clarification  as 
being  specifically  that  of  attention. 

The  conditions  of  attention  are  varied,  and  we  should 
describe  them  much  as  do  other  psychologists.  Briefly  con 
sidered,  we  may  say  that  they  are  both  external  and  internal 
to  the  organism.  Externally,  changes  of  stimulation  through 
addition,  subtraction,  and  alteration  of  stimuli  are  productive 
of  varying  degrees  of  clearness  in  conscious  contents.  Par 
ticipating  reciprocally  with  these  are  internal  conditions  of 
the  physiological  and  mental  state:  dispositional  traits,  con 
genital  and  acquired;  associative  connections;  the  imme 
diately  preceding  activities,  etc.  What  we  wish  to  insist 
upon  is  that  attention,  however  aroused,  has  the  sole  func 
tion  of  rendering  the  contents  upon  which  it  acts  vivid  and 
clear.  The  number  of  different  contents  that  may  emerge 
simultaneously  with  varying  degrees  of  clearness  is  a  problem 
of  the  'span  of  attention,'  or  more  properly  the  span  of 
awareness.  It  would  appear  that  several  different  contents 
may  manifest  themselves  in  this  way  simultaneously  from 


296  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

out  the  larger  field  of  Simple  Presentation.  The  field  of 
consciousness  is  a  shifting  mass  of  contents,  some  few  of 
which  emerge  into  clearness,  while  the  rest  constitute  a  sort 
of  undifferentiated  background. 

We  have  called  the  third  and  final  stage  of  consciousness 
Cognition  or  the  consciousness  of  knowing.  This  stage  is 
achieved  by  a  unique  function,  the  Relating  Activity,  which 
is  responsible  for  the  problem  or  task,  bearing  upon  the  data 
which  the  mind  affords.  The  selective  activity  of  this  func 
tion  is  different  from  that  of  attention,  since  it  selects  from 
a  "point  of  view."  It  groups  and  unifies  into  meaningful 
wholes  those  contents  which  have  been  offered  and  are  found 
suited  to  its  purpose.  All  the  stages  which  Westphal  differ 
entiates  are  determined  by  this  functional  activity.  Even 
the  erschliessbar  stage,  in  so  far  as  it  selects  relevant  data 
because  of  their  relevancy,  gives  evidence  of  relational  ac 
tivity,  though  it  be  quite  unconscious.  It  should  be  noted, 
however,  that  the  relevancy  of  such  contents  is  at  times 
fortuitous. 

A  further  analysis  of  relational  activity  may  be  under 
taken  from  many  different  angles.  We  have  already  ex 
plained  Westphal's  genesis  of  the  function  of  interpretation. 
Ernst  Durr  has  offered  a  useful  classification  of  the  relations 
in  his  revision  of  Ebbinghaus's  Grundzuge  der  Psychologie. 
Though  essentially  logical  in  its  form,  his  consideration  ap 
pears  to  be  based  upon  the  fundamentally  psychological 
act  of  relating  by  comparison.  There  are,  he  tells  us,1  four 
chief  types  of  relation:  similarity,  difference,  equality,  and 
identity.  To  this  list  he  adds,  though  he  does  not  develop, 
a  fifth  type,  Besonderheit  or  particularity.  This  relation 
would  appear  to  have  a  genetic  significance  by  intimating 
that  the  first  appearance  of  the  relational  function  is  a  crude 
setting-off  of  contents.  The  particularizing  of  parts  in  wholes 
is  a  primitive  differentiation  without  reference  to  an  explicit 
category.  Such  particularization  is  dichotomous,  emphasiz 
ing  the  part  which  is  thus  set  off  from  all  the  rest  of  expe 
rience.  Though  naturally  founded  upon  an  act  of  attention, 

i  Vol.  II,  p.  278. 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT  297 

particularization  is  still  distinguishable  from  emergence  into 
clearness.  Attention  selects  and  may  provoke  associative 
trends,  but  it  does  not  "set  off,"  for  it  involves  no  point  of 
view,  however  vague.  Attention  clarifies  discrete  contents, 
one  or  several.  To  particularize,  however,  is  to  group,  to 
assemble,  and  thus  set  off  a  part  from  all  the  rest  of  experi 
ence.  Out  of  this  primitive  function  arise  the  more  refined 
similarities  and  differences,  identities  and  equalities,  which 
summarize  abstractly  the  bases  of  our  logical  categories  and 
systems  of  knowledge. 

Other  lists  of  mental  functions,  including  the  relations, 
are  given  by  many  writers,  including  Stumpf  in  his  paper, 
"Erscheinungen  und  psychische  Funktionen,"  1  Calkins  in 
her  Introduction  to  Psychology,2  Dunlap  in  his  System  of 
Psychology,3  and  Coe  in  a  paper  entitled,  "A  Proposed 
Classification  of  Mental  Functions."  4  For  Stumpf  the  chief 
functions  are :  the  noting  of  '  appearances '  and  their  re 
lations,  the  combining  of  contents  into  complexes,  con 
ception,  apprehension  and  judgment,  feelings  of  agitation 
(Gemutsbewegungeri),  desire  and  volition.  He  does  not  of 
fer  this  as  an  exhaustive  list,  but  rather  as  illustrative  of 
the  distinction  he  is  drawing  between  function  and  content. 
Calkins  gives  a  tentative  list  of  the  relations,  while  Dunlap 
writes:  "As  examples  of  relations  which  are  probably  ele 
mentary  we  may  name  the  following:  difference,  identity, 
similarity,  greater,  less,  betweenness,  direction  (peculiar  to 
space),  a  relation  peculiar  to  time,  agreement,  and  possibly 
the  relations  of  good  and  bad.  At  any  rate,  it  is  difficult  to 
see  how  these  can  be  resolved  into  any  other  relations:  but 
the  list  is  only  a  suggestion."  Coe  gives  five  "biological" 
and  six  "preferential"  functions.  The  subdivisions  of  the 
first  group  are:  "i.  Increase  in  the  spatial  range  of  objects 
responded  to.  2.  Increase  in  the  temporal  range  of  objects 
responded  to.  3.  Increase  in  the  range  of  magnitudes  to 

1  Abh.  d.  kgl.  Akad.  d.  Wiss.  z.  Berlin,  1905. 
z  New  York,  ist  ed.,  1901,  pp.  I3of. 

3  New  York,  1912,  p.  149. 

4  Psychological  Review,  Vol.  XXII,  1915,  pp.  87-98. 


298  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

which  response  is  made.  4.  Increase  in  the  range  of  qualities 
responded  to.  5.  Increase  in  the  range  of  environmental 
co-ordinations  to  which  co-ordinated  responses  are  made." 
Those  of  the  second  group  are:  "i.  To  be  conscious.  2.  To 
multiply  objects  of  consciousness.  3 .  To  control  objects,  one 
self  included.  4.  To  unify  objects,  oneself  included.  5.  To 
communicate,  that  is,  have  in  common.  6.  To  contemplate." 
Each  of  these  lists  has  its  suggestive  value,  yet  none  of 
them  tells  us  very  much  about  the  analytic  nature  of  the 
functions  named.  If  we  assume  a  fundamental  impressi 
bility  which  is,  in  a  way,  the  function  of  experiencing  per  se 
and  the  occasion  of  all  presentations,  then  the  three  addi 
tional  functions  of  associating,  attending,  and  relating  seem 
to  furnish  us  with  a  means  of  analysing  all  the  more  complex 
activities  of  mind.  For  example,  let  us  consider  Stumpf  s 
list.  His  '  noting  of  appearances  '  would  be  the  same  as  our 
act  of  attention,  while  for  us  relations  are  not  'noted/  but 
cognized  or  known.  His  ' combination  into  complexes' 
would  appear  to  be  associative  in  the  main,  though  it  is 
probable  that  particularization  is  also  involved.  'Con 
ception'  is  but  the  act  of  relating  from  a  definite  and  re 
stricted  point  of  view.  'Apprehension'  is  defined  with  less 
certainty,  for  it  may  mean  presentation,  awareness,  or  cog 
nition.  'Judgment'  may  be  defined  as  an  expressed  rela 
tionship,  i.  e.,  one  falling  within  Westphal's  fourth  stage  of 
consciousness.  Functionally,  it  is  hardly  to  be  distinguished 
from  the  act  of  conception,  except  in  so  far  as  the  latter 
involves  a  more  complex  series  of  judgments  that  are  cumu 
lative  and  thus  give  rise  to  the  'concept'  which  is  a  general 
idea.  We  might  similarly  distinguish  inference  as  being  a 
series  of  judgments,  not  cumulative,  but  leading  to  a  final 
judgment.  All  such  logical  distinctions  are  essentially  one 
in  the  fact  that  they  involve  the  establishment  of  more  or  less 
subtle  relations.  The  affective  and  volitional  functions 
which  Stumpf  adds  to  his  list  are  somewhat  different.  Here 
the  aesthetic  and  the  ethical  are  suggested.  Yet  it  is  doubtful 
if  a  unique  function  can  be  discovered  in  the  acts  of  will 
or  emotion,  in  appreciation  or  desire.  The  differentiae  are 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT  299 

more  especially  due  to  formulations  resting  upon  the  precise 
contents  that  enter  into  the  associational,  attentional,  and 
relational  acts.  Affections  undoubtedly  arise  in  functional 
settings,  yet  we  may  conclude,  tentatively  at  least,  that 
these  arise  as  affective  contents,  and  not  as  functions. 

Calkins'  and  Dunlap's  lists  need  not  detain  us,  for  they 
are  expressly  lists  of  the  relations.  Coe's  *  biological'  func 
tions  likewise  may  be  dismissed  because  we  are  dealing  now 
with  mental  rather  than  with  physiological  activity.  The 
connection  is  not  so  remote,  however,  as  this  summary  dis 
missal  might  suggest.  As  regards  Coe's  first  two  f  preferen 
tial'  functions,  'to  be  conscious'  and  'to  multiply  objects  of 
consciousness,'  these  appear  to  be  embraced  by  the  general 
function  of  experiencing  per  se  that  we  have  assumed.  The 
third  and  fourth,  'to  control'  and  'to  unify  objects,  oneself 
included,'  involve  association,  attention,  and  relation  in 
varying  degrees  which  the  specific  acts  alone  would  indicate. 
The  fifth  function,  'communication,'  is  based  upon  reflexes 
and  may  be  to  some  extent  instinctive,  yet  it  involves  re 
lational  acts  manifest  at  the  stage  of  cognition,  since  it  ex 
presses  a  formulated  knowledge.  'Contemplation,'  the  sixth 
of  these  functions,  is  also  a  relational  activity.  Its  unique 
ness  as  experience  seems  to  rest  upon  a  certain  immediacy  of 
the  related  contents.  Without  seeking  after  points  of  view 
or  categories  to  classify  with,  and  without  motivating  re 
actions  of  an  adjustive  sort,  we  take  the  object  of  contem 
plation  at  its  face  value.  It  has  no  ulterior  meanings.  This 
implies  subtleties  of  usage,  but  it  hardly  proclaims  the  pres 
ence  of  a  unique  function. 

Although  we  have  done  scant  justice  to  many  of  the  sug 
gestions  included  in  these  lists,  our  comment  may  perhaps 
serve  to  indicate  that  the  functions  of  association,  attention, 
and  relation  can  be  applied  in  a  reasonably  broad  and  in 
clusive  manner,  without  losing  their  distinction. 

Returning  to  our  revised  stages  of  consciousness,  it  must 
be  admitted  that  the  term  "stages,"  which  we  carried  over 
from  Westphal,  is  not  quite  so  appropriate  in  our  scheme  as 
it  was  in  his.  Westphal's  stages  are  the  steps  of  a  progressive 


300  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

development  which  may  terminate  at  any  one,  leaving  those 
above  it  unattained.  In  the  typical  instance  this  is  true  of 
Presentation,  Awareness,  and  Cognition.  Many  mental 
objects  remain  at  the  level  of  simple  presentation,  while  a 
few  emerge  into  attentional  clearness,  to  become,  all  or  part, 
the  subject  of  further  selection  by  the  relating  function. 
One  cannot  insist,  however,  that  the  last  two  stages  must  in 
variably  follow  in  the  order  named.  Westphal  has  pointed 
out  that  the  different  stages  he  names  are  accomplished  with 
varying  degrees  of  attention  and  that  they  are  quite  inde 
pendent  of  attention  as  such.  Still,  he  has  not  shown  that 
contents  which  are  cognized  are  ever  totally  without  the 
range  of  attention.  For  evidence  of  this  sort  we  must  turn 
to  explorations  in  the  debatable  land  of  the  'sub-conscious ' 
and  the  'unconscious.'  Here  we  find  suggestion,  if  not 
proof,  of  a  wider  range  of  relational  activity  than  is  normally 
met  with.  Cases  such  as  those  of  'double  personality,' 
where  the  individual  seems  able  to  converse  on  one  theme 
while  writing  automatically,  yet  intelligently,  upon  another, 
call  for  special  consideration.  Therefore,  we  shall  not  deny 
the  possibility  of  a  relational  activity  of  some  order  imme 
diately  upon  presentation.  More  importance  attaches  to 
the  essential  difference  in  the  three  functions  than  to  a  fixed 
order  of  their  appearance. 

The  doctrine  of  these  discrete  functions  suggests  a  general 
interpretation  of  psychology  and  is  significant  for  many  re 
lated  disciplines  such  as  education,  the  normative  sciences, 
and  epistemology.  For  education,  concerned  as  it  is  with 
the  process  of  learning  and  the  development  of  personality 
and  character,  it  is  evident  that  the  functions  of  association 
and  attention,  although  of  fundamental  importance,  are  yet 
inadequate.  The  growth  of  intelligence  rests  upon  the  unique 
activity  of  relating.  This  is  the  truly  creative  function  of 
mind.  Association  and  attention  are  in  some  measure  inde 
pendent  of  individual  initiative.  The  mere  sequence  of  con 
scious  events,  and  of  associated  acts  of  behavior,  may  pro 
vide  learning  of  a  kind,  but  it  is  arbitrary  and  non-selective. 
The  relating  of  contents  furnishes  the  sole  method  of  gaining 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT  301 

insight  and  knowledge.  By  an  appropriate  selection  of  ob 
jects  and  the  conditions  of  their  presentation,  one  can  force 
upon  a  pupil  the  acts  of  association  and  attention.  The  re 
lating  act  is  more  strictly  individual  and  is  much  less  com 
pletely  within  the  control  of  the  instructor.  Presentation 
and  awareness  condition  thought,  but  thinking,  or  the  es 
tablishment  of  meanings,  follows  the  individual's  own 
initiative.  This  is  why  teaching  depends  so  largely  upon  the 
art  of  arousing  interest  and  individual  responsiveness.  A 
deal  of  unsound  pedagogy  is  rooted  in  the  theory  that  to 
attend  and  to  associate  is  all  that  is  necessary  in  order  to 
know.  The  case  of  the  imbecile  who  may  be  quite  proficient 
in  association  and  attention,  yet  without  the  ability  to  relate 
cogently,  is  a  striking  evidence  of  the  fallacy  of  this  view. 
Mental  tests  indicate  that  individuals  of  sub-normal  intelli 
gence  may  be  able  to  perform  mathematical  operations  in 
addition,  subtraction,  multiplication,  and  division  as  well  as, 
and  sometimes  better  than,  normal  individuals  of  their 
mental  age.  But  when  more  concrete  problems  are  set, 
such  as  that  of  determining  the  amount  a  farmer  receives  for 
639  bushels  of  wheat  at  $.98  a  bushel,  they  are  unable  to 
comprehend  the  relations. 

The  normative  sciences,  logic,  ethics,  and  aesthetics,  treat 
each  of  a  special  mode  of  relationship  from  a  certain  point 
of  view.1  It  is  likewise  through  the  establishment  of  rela 
tions  that  the  foundations  of  a  theory  of  knowledge  are  laid. 
Reality  is  a  product  of  relational  activity.  The  adequacy  of 
any  such  concept  is  determined  by  the  nature  of  the  demand 
for  existential  facts  to  justify  relations  which  the  mind 
establishes.2 

These  brief  comments  must  suffice,  in  order  that  we  may 
devote  the  remainder  of  our  paper  to  a  consideration  of  the 
conscious  contents  upon  which  the  mental  functions  operate. 
We  may  designate  the  elemental  contents  as  being  of  four 

1  Cf.  the  author,  An  Introduction  to  General  Psychology,  New  York,  1914, 
pp.  253ff. 

2  Cf.  the  author,  "The  Relation  of  Psychology  to  Philosophy  and  Edu 
cation,"  Psychological  Review,  Vol.  XX,  1913,  pp.  i86ff. 


302  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

kinds:  sensations,  images,  affections,  and  thoughts.  Of  the 
first  three  classes  we  shall  say  but  little,  since  all  are  com 
monly  accepted  and  their  respective  characteristics  reason 
ably  well  known.  Association,  attention,  and  relation  act 
upon  elements  of  each  of  these  classes  and  likewise  upon 
their  attributes.  The  contents  of  thought  demand  some 
special  consideration,  both  because  they  have  been  fre 
quently  rejected  and  because  they  are  dependent  for  their 
existence  upon  the  function  of  relation. 

The  unfavorable  reaction  which  attended  the  discussion 
of  'imageless'  thought  was  largely  due  to  the  insistence  of 
its  critics  that  these  contents  should  substantiate  their  claim 
to  existence  by  direct  comparison  with  the  accepted  elements, 
sensation,  image,  and  affection.  The  criteria  advanced  by 
structural  psychology,  especially  those  concerning  the  at 
tributes,  were  not  appropriate  for  a  convincing  demonstra 
tion.  It  is  upon  functional  rather  than  upon  structural 
grounds  that  the  thought  contents  must  be  considered. 
Indeed,  but  for  an  explanation  of  their  existence  such  as  is 
afforded  by  the  doctrine  of  mental  acts  of  relation,  thought 
contents  would  have  no  place  in  systematic  psychology. 
They  are  not  contents  which  can  be  described  in  terms  of 
extensity  or  intensity.  Their  duration  is  difficult  to  deter 
mine,  and  while  their  qualities  are  unique,  they  are  not  sub 
ject  to  a  classification  such  as  we  can  apply  to  the  other 
elements.1  The  question  as  to  the  existence  of  thought 
elements  resolves  itself  into  the  question  of  a  structural 
versus  a  functional  psychology.  We  must  therefore  recon 
sider  our  foundations  before  we  can  justify  the  acceptance 
of  this  new  category  of  conscious  contents. 

In  a  purely  structural  psychology  existential  qualifications 
are  paramount.  In  so  far  as  the  province  of  psychology  is 
limited  to  the  existential  facts 'adduced  from  introspective 
description  and  analysis,  it  is  difficult  to  establish  any  ele 
ment  save  sensation.  For  this  reason  neither  affection  nor 
the  image  can  be  said  to  have  won  an  incontestable  place  in 
the  scheme  of  elements.  Yet,  even  though  we  assume  all 

1  Cf.  K.  Biihler,  Arch.  f.  d.  ges.  Psychol.,  Vol.  IX,  1907,  pp.  315,  36if. 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT  303 

three  elements  with  their  respective  attributes,  and  the 
usual  views  regarding  association,  memory,  attention,  etc., 
still  the  interpretation  of  human  action  and  conduct  is  in 
complete.  Realizing  this,  the  behaviorists  support  their 
point  of  view  by  contending  that  the  results  of  introspection 
are  not  practical.  At  least,  it  must  be  admitted  that  the 
basis  for  an  applied  psychology  receives  but  scanty  consid 
eration  in  the  restricted  program  of  the  structuralist.  As  a 
result,  the  interests  of  many  psychologists  seem  to  waver  at 
present  between  mental  tests,  on  the  one  hand,  and  recourse 
to  physiology,  on  the  other.  To  be  of  use,  mind  must  func 
tion.  For  those  who  find  the  problem  of  mental  activity  no 
less  worthy  of  investigation  than  the  problem  of  an  organ 
ism's  action-system,  the  need  of  a  more  thorough-going 
functional  psychology  than  we  now  possess  is  quite  evident. 

The  mental  functions  here  advanced  as  a  contribution  to 
the  solution  of  this  problem  are  three  in  number:  Association, 
Attention,  and  Relation.  The  first  operates,  or  may  op 
erate,  at  all  stages  of  consciousness,  including  even  the  hy 
pothetical  stage  of  Simple  Presentation.  The  second  op 
erates  at  the  stages  of  Awareness  and  Cognition,  while  the 
third  acts  typically,  though  perhaps  not  exclusively,  at  the 
last  stage,  that  of  Cognition.  By  means  of  association, 
contents  are  connected  by  bonds  conditioned  through  simul 
taneity  or  close  succession  in  experience.  By  means  of  at 
tention,  certain  contents  emerge  into  consciousness  by  rea 
son  of  the  clearness  or  vividness  which  is  thus  attached  to 
them.  By  means  of  relation,  contents  are  set  off  and  com 
pared  with  one  another;  they  are  received  or  rejected  as 
suited  or  unsuited  to  the  purpose  of  the  problem  at  hand: 
in  the  final  step  they  are  formulated  and  established  as 
meanings. 

Strictly  speaking,  no  one  of  these  functions  need  be  de 
scribed  as  conscious  in  order  to  effect  its  end.  We  experience 
association  not  so  much  through  a  consciousness  of  the  as 
sociative  bond,  as  through  the  facts  of  revival.  Yet  associa 
tions  must  have  been  formed  before  a  revival  can  take  place. 
Similarly  attention  is  marked  by  the  attributive  clearness  of 


304  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  content  rather  than  by  an  aspect  of  consciousness  which 
is  itself  the  act  of  attention.  As  for  relation,  although  it 
occurs  typically  at  a  stage  of  consciousness  more  accessible 
to  observation,  the  act  of  relating  need  not  itself  be  a  con 
scious  act.  No  mental  activity  is  of  necessity  a  conscious 
activity.  Still,  it  would  be  perverse  logic  to  require  that 
relational  acts  must  be  unconscious  because  association  and 
attention  are  commonly  so  judged. 

But  what  is  the  conscious  mark  of  a  relating  act?  It 
is  an  element  of  thought,  the  consciousness  of  relation.  Two 
straight  lines  of  unequal  length  may  be  regarded  as  differing 
in  length,  as  like  or  unlike  in  direction,  or  as  alike  in  being 
straight.  These  aspects  are  conscious  factors  that  change 
as  the  sensed  contents,  or  their  attributes,  are  variously  re 
lated.  The  act  of  relation  may  be  attended  by  a  unique  ele 
ment  of  consciousness  which  is  imageless,  i.  e.,  non-sensory 
and  non-affective.  The  doctrine  of  the  'threshold'  may  ob 
tain  here  as  it  does  for  sensation.  Still  the  consciousness  of 
the  relation  is  not  an  existential  content  in  the  same  way  in 
which  a  sensation  is,  for  it  is  tied  to  the  contents  that  are 
being  related.  The  terms  being  related  constitute  its  founda 
tion,  and  the  relation  subsists,  as  it  were,  upon  these  founda 
tions.  Relational  elements  are  not  independent;  they  are 
not  'free'  ideas.  Yet  from  them,  from  the  mind's  capacity 
to  particularize,  then  to  differentiate  from  a  point  of  view, 
then  to  equate,  identify,  compare,  etc.,  there  gradually 
evolve  the  'free'  ideas,  the  independent,  existential  mean 
ings  which  we  may  term  the  notions  of  things.  From  a  cer 
tain  conscious  relation  of  lines  comes  the  notion  of  length; 
from  others  come  the  notions  of  direction,  straightness, 
equality,  inequality,  etc.  Notions  thus  created  constitute 
an  additional  fund  of  contents,  which  in  their  turn  may  be 
acted  upon  by  association,  by  attention,  and  by  the  relating 
function.  In  this  manner  we  are  enabled  to  create  and  en 
rich  our  mental  furnishings,  to  enlarge  the  scope  of  our  ideas, 
and  to  bring  meaning  into  what  would  otherwise  be  a  chaos. 
Not  all  relational  acts  are  productive  of  'felt'  contents.  Yet 
the  act  of  relation  conditions  such  a  conscious  insight,  just 


MENTAL  ACTIVITY  AND  CONSCIOUS  CONTENT  305 

as  the  act  of  attention  conditions  clear  contents,  and  the  act 
of  association,  among  other  things,  conditions  the  image. 

It  is  the  process  of  abstraction  that  makes  possible  the 
crystallization  of  the  notion  from  the  tied  but  'felt'  relations. 
Relational  aspects,  subsisting  in  perceptual  and  ideational 
complexes,  are  known  and  may  be  nucleated  and  detached 
from  their  settings.  We  call  this  abstraction.  Possibly  it 
is  a  unique  function,  yet  such  an  assumption  is  hardly  neces 
sary.  Abstraction  may  be  regarded  as  an  act  of  relation 
whose  terms  are  the  conscious  relations  already  subsisting  in 
other  relational  processes.  In  this  manner  a  relation  is  lifted 
out  of  its  subsistency  and  achieves  independent  existence. 
It  is  abstracted  from  its  context.  As  a  very  simple  example,  a 
child  is  shown  an  apple  and  an  orange.  They  are  so  pre 
sented  that  the  likenesses  of  the  two  as  regards  rotundity  and 
edibility  are  emphasized.  A  likeness  of  impression  and  re 
sponse  is  thus  'felt'  in  noting  the  two  objects.  Two  relations 
are  established,  for  each  is  round  and  each  may  be  eaten. 
When,  however,  the  two  similarities  are  compared,  the  con 
cept  or  notion  of  similarity  itself  may  become  the  object  of 
thought.  Rotundity  and  edibility  are  based  upon  quite  dif 
ferent  sensory  contents  yet  the  likeness  of  an  apple  to  an 
orange  in  being  rotund,  and  the  likeness  of  the  same  two 
objects  in  being  edible,  can  be  related  and  thus  coalesce  to 
form  one  abstract  notion  of  similarity.  This  example  is  far 
too  simple.  No  child  gains  abstract  knowledge  so  easily. 
Instead  of  a  single  relation  of  relations,  many  must  be 
formed  before  the  aspect  to  be  identified  can  be  lifted  out 
of  its  various  concrete  settings.  Nevertheless,  the  process  of 
abstraction  appears  to  be  given  an  explanation  in  some  such 
way  as  this.  If  the  explanation  is  satisfactory,  abstraction 
may  be  placed  among  the  relations,  which  obviates  the 
necessity  of  a  special  category  for  it. 

Introspective  evidence  for  the  existence  of  notions  which 
embody  the  meanings  of  past  experiences  is  very  strong. 
Competent  observers  report  an  experience  of  the  meaning 
'  red,'  yet  they  are  aware  of  its  image  neither  as  a  quality 
nor  as  a  word.  Likewise,  they  report  the  presence  of  such 


306  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

meanings  as  straightness,  curvedness,  direction,  length, 
squareness,  roundness,  without  imagery,  pictorial  or  verbal, 
and  without  kinaesthesis.  Three-dimensional  geometric  con 
cepts,  points  of  view,  human  qualities  of  goodness,  badness, 
beauty,  ugliness,  truth,  and  falsity,  all  seem  to  exist  in 
notional  form  to  be  operated  upon,  associated,  attended  to, 
and  related,  as  entities  equally  distinct  and  independent 
with  those  of  the  sensational  and  imaginal  order. 

It  is  the  act  of  relation  that  gives  meaning,  but  not  neces 
sarily  as  a  conscious  content,  though  this  occurs  with  the  'felt' 
relation.  Meanings  of  previous  formation  may  be  abstracted 
and  revived  as  notions,  thus  constituting  a  further  category 
of  thought-elements.  As  contents,  relations  subsist  in  the 
conscious  stream,  inasmuch  as  they  are  always  dependent 
upon  other  contents  between  which  the  relation  is  estab 
lished.  But  notions  are  truly  existential  and  take  their  place 
among  the  entities  of  consciousness  along  with  the  sensa 
tions,  the  images,  and  the  affections. 

Functional  psychology  may  freely  accept  all  the  facts  a 
structuralist  can  demonstrate,  as  well  as  all  those  the  be- 
haviorist  may  adduce.  Yet  over  and  above  the  aims  of  these 
investigators,  the  functionalist  proposes  a  study  of  mental 
activity  and  its  bearings  both  upon  conscious  content  and 
upon  behavior.  Much  remains  to  be  done  before  the  various 
functions  can  be  regarded  as  fixed,  or  the  scope  of  their  in 
fluence  fully  understood.  In  the  course  of  more  detailed 
experimentation  and  theoretical  consideration,  many  changes 
in  such  a  scheme  as  here  offered  may  be  expected.  The 
obvious  connection  of  mental  functions  with  physiological 
processes  calls  for  a  comprehensive  examination.  We  must 
learn  more  of  the  influence  of  mental  acts  upon  the  nature 
of  conscious  contents,  especially  the  affections.  The  bear 
ings  of  mentality  upon  behavior  are  very  obscure.  All  these 
are  problems  which  we  can  more  readily  set  than  solve.  Yet 
if  our  proposals  but  commend  themselves  as  a  program  for 
further  investigation,  we  have  at  least  defined  our  aims. 
The  way  is  then  open  for  the  more  detailed  and  arduous  task 
of  determining  the  precise  nature  and  connection  of  mental 
activity  and  conscious  content. 


THE  ROLE  OF  INTENT  IN  MENTAL  FUNCTIONING 
JOHN  WALLACE  BAIRD 

AN  important  contribution  to  psychology  has  resulted 
from  the  investigation  of  the  influence  which  one's  purpose 
or  intent  or  point  of  view  exerts  in  determining  and  directing 
one's  mental  processes.  Numerous  investigators  have  at 
tacked  the  problem,  and  their  findings  agree  in  testifying 
to  the  fact  that  the  intent  is  of  paramount  significance  in 
mental  functioning.  The  findings  of  these  investigators  un 
doubtedly  bring  us  nearer  to  an  understanding  of  the  nature 
and  the  magnitude  of  this  *  intentional'  influence;  but  they 
still  leave  us  in  doubt  as  to  the  details  of  the  mental  mechan 
ism  by  means  of  which  it  is  exerted  and  controlled. 

The  phenomenon  is  a  familiar  one,  at  least  in  certain  of  its 
grosser  and  more  general  aspects.  Every  normal  individual 
finds  that  he  is  somehow  capable  of  directing  his  mental 
energies,  more  or  less  at  will,  to  the  solving  of  any  problem 
which  he  may  choose  to  attack;  he  finds,  too,  that  having 
once  selected  his  problem,  he  is  capable  of  holding  himself 
tenaciously  to  his  task.  He  observes,  meanwhile,  that  his 
mental  procedure  consists  essentially  in  adhering  rigidly  to 
a  consistent  train  of  ideas,  and  that  that  in  turn  involves 
an  excluding  or  banishing  of  such  ideas  and  ideational  trains 
as  are  extraneous  and  irrelevant  to  his  task. 

This  selective  and  directive  function  seems  to  be  an  es 
sential  characteristic  of  all  mental  activity.  Its  presence 
and  potency  are  no  less  evident  at  the  lower  levels  of  ob 
serving,  learning,  and  remembering  than  at  the  higher  levels 
of  abstracting,  judging,  and  reasoning.  The  reader  who 
sets  himself  the  task  of  mastering  the  meaning  of  an  author 
may  become  so  absorbed  in  his  reading  that  he  wholly  fails 
to  notice  other  stimuli  from  his  environment  which,  under 
other  conditions,  would  undoubtedly  be  observed  and  noted. 
He  fails  to  observe  misprints  and  misspelled  words  in  the 


308  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

text  which  he  is  reading.  His  process  of  observing  is  essen 
tially  a  selective  process, — certain  stimuli  find  access  to 
his  consciousness  while  others  find  that  their  entrance  is 
barred.  This  process  of  selecting  takes  place  under  the 
direction  of  the  task  which  he  has  undertaken  or  the  purpose 
which  he  has  in  view.  And  the  directive  power  of  the  task 
may  reach  such  magnitude  as  to  distort  one's  apprehension 
of  the  object  to  be  observed,  the  distortion  being  in  conform 
ity  with  the  ideational  train  induced  by  the  task;  the  reader 
actually  misperceives  the  misprinted  words  and  apprehends 
the  text  as  though  it  were  printed  in  conventional  verbal 
forms.  That  'suggestion'  and  'expectation'  exert  an  in 
fluence  upon  the  process  and  the  product  of  observing  is  a 
commonplace. 

If,  however,  the  reader  of  our  illustration  should  adopt 
the  point  of  view  of  the  proof-reader,  if  he  should  read  the 
text  with  the  intent  to  discover  typographical  errors,  his 
change  in  attitude  would  bring  with  it  a  corresponding 
change  in  mental  product.  On  the  positive  side,  he  would 
now  detect  misprints  which  formerly  escaped  his  notice; 
but  on  the  negative  side,  he  would  obtain  a  less  definite  and 
detailed  knowledge  of  the  author's  meaning. 

The  degree  to  which  one's  intent  determines  what  shall 
be  observed  and  what  shall  be  ignored  has  been  brought  to 
light  in  various  experimental  investigations.  Myers  l  and 
others  have  found  that  students  of  average  intelligence  are 
wholly  unable  to  recall  certain  details  of  familiar  objects, — 
the  sizes  of  coins,  bank  notes,  and  postage  stamps;  the  num 
ber  of  steps  in  a  familiar  stairway;  the  number  and  arrange 
ment  of  windows  in  a  familiar  building;  the  furnishings  of  a 
familiar  room,  and  the  like, — the  obvious  reason  being  that 
these  details  failed  to  be  observed  because  of  a  lack  of  in 
tention  to  observe  them.  Myers  found,  too,  that  when  he 
exposed  a  group  of  letters  with  the  instruction  that  the  O's 
in  the  group  were  to  be  counted,  the  observers  succeeded  in 
accomplishing  this  task  but  failed  to  observe  what  other 

1  Garry  C.  Myers,  "  A  Study  in  Incidental  Memory,"  Archives  of  Psy 
chology,  No.  26,  1913. 


THE  ROLE  OF  INTENT  IN  MENTAL  FUNCTIONING         309 

letters  were  present,  what  was  the  arrangement  of  the  let 
ters,  and  what  was  the  color  of  the  background;  in  short, 
they  observed  only  that  feature  of  the  complex  which  they 
had  intended  to  observe,  and  all  of  the  other  features  escaped 
their  notice. 

Kulpe's  findings  l  show  that  the  intent  to  observe  may  be 
of  a  highly  differentiated  sort;  and  that  each  differentiation 
of  intent  results  in  a  highly  differentiated  result  of  observa 
tion.  In  this  investigation,  groups  of  nonsense-syllables  were 
exposed  for  a  brief  period  of  time  and  various  tasks  were 
assigned  to  the  observers.  In  one  case  they  were  instructed 
to  observe  how  many  letters  were  present;  in  another  case, 
to  observe  the  general  form  of  the  group;  in  another  case, 
to  observe  the  colors  of  the  letters;  in  a  fourth  case,  to  ob 
serve  the  syllables  themselves;  while  in  a  fifth  case  no  specific 
task  was  assigned.  Kulpe's  results  show  that  that  feature 
of  the  complex  upon  which  the  intent  was  directed  in  any 
case  was  usually  observed  with  twofold  greater  accuracy  and 
completeness  than  were  the  features  which  did  not  fall 
within  the  range  of  the  task.  For  instance,  when  the  ob 
servers  were  assigned  the  task  of  noting  the  colors  of  the 
letters,  they  made  a  score  of  sixty  per  cent  correct  in  the 
observing  of  these  colors  but  of  only  thirty  per  cent  correct 
in  observing  how  many  letters  and  what  syllables  were 
present;  when  instructed  to  observe  how  many  letters  were 
present  they  accomplished  this  task  with  a  degree  of  ac 
curacy  amounting  to  sixty-three  per  cent,  but  the  accuracy 
of  their  observation  of  the  colors  now  dropped  to  thirty-five 
per  cent.  Besides  furnishing  a  quantitative  measurement 
of  the  significance  of  these  differentiated  and  artificially 
imposed  intents,  Kiilpe's  findings  show  that  when  no  specific 
task  is  assigned,  certain  features  of  his  complex  stimuli  were 
more  accurately  and  more  completely  observed  than  other 
features, — form  being  most  accurately  perceived,  while  num 
ber  was  least  accurately  perceived.  This  latter  finding  in 
dicates  that  the  human  individual  possesses  certain  natural 

1  O.  Kiilpe,  "Versuche  iiber  Abstraktion,"  Bericht  tiber  den  I.  Kongrtss 
fiir  experimentelle  Psychologic,  Leipzig,  1904,  pp.  56-68. 


310  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

or  habitual  intents  and  attitudes,  or  that  certain  features  of 
a  complex  situation  are  inherently  more  'interesting'  than 
other  features. 

The  influence  of  intent  is  equally  significant  in  the  process 
of  learning;  and  here,  too,  the  intent  may  be  of  a  highly 
differentiated  sort.  That  learning  cannot  be  readily  accom 
plished  by  an  individual  who  does  not  really  intend  to  learn 
is  shown  by  an  incident  reported  by  Radossawljewitsch.1 
The  experiment  consisted  in  exposing  a  list  of  nonsense- 
syllables,  the  arrangement  being  that  the  syllables  should 
be  presented  over  and  over  again  until  the  learner  signalled 
that  he  had  memorized  them.  On  account  of  unfamiliarity 
with  the  language,  one  of  his  observers  failed  to  understand 
that  his  task  was  to  consist  in  learning  the  syllables.  It 
turned  out  that,  in  the  absence  of  an  intent  to  learn,  the  suc 
cessive  presentations  of  the  series  proved  to  be  almost  wholly 
barren  of  result  in  the  case  of  this  observer;  forty-six  readings 
of  the  syllables  under  these  conditions  gave  rise  to  a  lesser 
degree  of  learning-effect  than  resulted  from  ten  readings 
when  the  intent  to  learn  was  present. 

Not  only,  however,  must  one  will  to  learn,  but  as  numerous 
investigations  have  shown,  one  must  will  to  learn  for  a  par 
ticular  purpose  and  in  a  particular  way  if  the  best  results 
are  to  be  achieved.  Aall 2  reports  a  series  of  experiments  in 
which  he  presented  materials  to  be  learned  by  six  hundred 
children.  In  one  case  he  stated  that  their  remembrance 
would  be  tested  on  the  following  day;  in  another  case  he 
stated  that  the  test  would  take  place  after  the  lapse  of  several 
weeks.  Instead,  however,  of  following  this  plan  as  stated  to 
the  children,  he  deferred  the  test  of  all  of  his  learners  for  a 
period  of  a  month  or  more.  It  turned  out  that  these  delayed 
reproductions  were  more  accurate  and  more  complete  in  the 
case  where  the  material  had  been  learned  with  the  intent  to 
remember  it  for  a  considerable  period. 

1  P.  Radossawljewitsch,  Das  Behalten  und  Vergessen  bei  Kindern  und 
Erwachsenen,  Leipzig,  1907,  p.  127. 

2  A.  Aall,  "Ein  neues  Gedachtnisgesetz?  "  Zeitschrift  fur  Psychologies 
Vol.  LXVI,  1913,  pp.  1-50. 


THE  ROLE  OF  INTENT  IN  MENTAL  FUNCTIONING         311 

The  purpose  for  which  a  given  act  of  learning  is  under 
taken  may  vary  between  wide  limits.  In  numerous  instances 
data  are  memorized  exclusively  for  the  purpose  of  immediate 
recall;  in  other  cases  it  is  the  purpose  of  the  learner  to  acquire 
a  permanent  remembrance  of  the  data.  When  we  consult 
the  telephone  directory,  we  ordinarily  make  no  attempt  to 
remember  the  telephone  number  permanently;  we  wish  to 
retain  it  in  memory  only  long  enough  to  transmit  it  to  the 
operator,  after  which  we  usually  forget  it  forthwith.  This 
type  of  purely  temporary  acquisition,  for  use  in  the  imme 
diate  future,  is  exceedingly  frequent,  and  exceedingly  val 
uable,  in  our  everyday  activities;  and  a  characteristic  in 
tent  or  attitude  is  involved  in  the  process  of  acquiring  data 
for  temporary  as  opposed  to  permanent  retention. 

In  writing  from  dictation  the  stenographer  endeavors  to 
carry  the  dictated  material  in  mind  only  long  enough  to 
permit  of  its  being  transcribed  to  paper;  and  Bryan  and 
Harter's  study  of  the  acquisition  of  telegraphy  1  reports  that 
in  receiving  messages  it  is  the  custom  of  skilled  teleg 
raphers  to  lag  behind,  since  this  procedure  enables  them  to 
get  a  better  survey  of  the  material  and  hence  a  clearer  appre 
hension  of  it,  before  committing  it  to  paper.  It  is  essential, 
however,  that  so  soon  as  the  stenographer  or  the  telegrapher 
transcribes  any  group  of  words,  he  should  thereupon  forget 
them  and  devote  his  attention  to  the  following  group.  The 
phenomenon  of  temporary  retention  and  subsequent  dis 
missal  from  memory  is  a  valuable  asset  here  as  in  numerous 
other  instances.  For  example,  in  the  answering  of  questions 
we  seek  to  retain  the  question  in  memory  only  long  enough 
for  our  immediate  purposes  of  answering;  the  student  who 
draws  from  a  model,  or  the  histologist  who  draws  from  a 
microscopic  slide,  must  possess  this  capacity  of  temporary 
retention  and  immediate  reproduction  in  order  to  proceed 

1  W.  L.  Bryan  and  N.  Harter,  "  Studies  in  the  Physiology  and  Psychol 
ogy  of  the  Telegraphic  Language,"  Psychological  Review,  Vol.  IV,  1897, 
pp.  27-53;  Vol.  VI,  1899,  pp.  345-375-  See  also  W.  F.  Book,  "The  Psy 
chology  of  Skill,"  University  of  Montana  Publications  in  Psychology, 
Vol.  I,  1908. 


3 1 2  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

efficiently  with  his  task.  There  are  numerous  instances 
where  maximum  efficiency  of  performance  demands  that, 
after  delivering  an  address  on  a  particular  topic  and  upon  a 
particular  occasion,  the  speaker  should  thereupon  forget  all 
about  it  and  turn  his  attention  to  other  matters;  or  where 
the  lawyer,  after  having  first  saturated  himself  with  all  avail 
able  knowledge  regarding  a  case,  and  after  having  then 
made  use  of  this  particular  store  of  knowledge  in  pleading  his 
case,  should  promptly  forget  at  least  the  details  in  order  to 
devote  his  mental  energies  to  another  case.  And  it  is  in  con 
sequence  of  the  diversity  of  learning-intent,  with  the  con 
sequent  diversity  of  learning-effect,  that  this  state  of  affairs 
is  possible. 

These  illustrations  show  that  the  act  of  learning  may  be 
undertaken  for  wholly  different  purposes  and  that  the  intent 
of  the  learner  may  vary  widely.  The  degree  to  which  this 
specialization  and  differentiation  of  intent  in  learning  may 
be  carried  is  shown  in  numerous  investigations  of  the  Lern- 
prozess.  Investigators  in  this  field  have  devised  a  consider 
able  number  and  variety  of  methods  of  testing  the  effect  of 
learning,  and  these  methods  differ  widely  from  one  another 
in  nature  and  in  principle.  Now  it  frequently  happens  in 
laboratory  investigations  that,  before  undertaking  his  task 
of  learning,  the  learner  inquires  what  method  is  to  be  em 
ployed  in  the  subsequent  test  of  his  remembrance.  The  ex 
perienced  learner  has  at  his  command  a  variety  of  procedures, 
and  in  any  given  case  he  tends  to  employ  that  procedure  in 
learning  which  seems  most  appropriate  and  economical  in 
view  of  the  nature  of  the  test  which  will  subsequently  be 
employed.  Not  until  he  knows  what  test  will  be  employed 
does  he  feel  prepared  to  enter  upon  his  task  of  learning. 

The  fact  that  each  differentiation  of  intent  in  learning  has 
its  own  peculiar  differentiation  of  learning-effect  has  been 
demonstrated  by  Meumann.1  This  investigator  found  that 
when  retention  is  tested  by  means  of  the  method  of  paired 

1 E.  Meumann,  "Beobachtungen  iiber  differenzierte  Einstellung  bei 
Gedachtnisversuchen,"  Ze itschrift  fiir  pddagogische  Psychologie,  Vol.  XIII, 
1912,  pp.  456-463. 


THE  ROLE  OF  INTENT  IN  MENTAL  FUNCTIONING         313 

associates,1  the  experienced  learner  tends  to  memorize  only 
the  second  member  of  each  pair  of  syllables;  he  persists  in 
this  selective  procedure  even  when  he  is  required  to  read 
the  material  in  trochaic  rhythm,  that  is,  when  in  reading  the 
syllables  he  is  obliged  to  accentuate  the  initial  member  of 
each  pair.  And  it  frequently  happens  that  the  learner  who 
is  able  to  make  a  perfect  score  in  the  test  (that  is,  who  is 
able  to  reproduce  all  of  the  even-numbered  syllables  of  the 
series)  is  wholly  unable  to  reproduce  the  odd-numbered 
syllables.  It  would  appear  that  the  learner  had  here  been 
content  to  hold  the  experimenter  responsible  for  the  repro 
ducing  of  the  odd-numbered  syllables  and  had  devoted  him 
self  almost  exclusively  to  the  learning  of  the  even-numbered 
syllables,  and  that  he  has  done  this  notwithstanding  the  fact 
that  in  his  reading  of  the  syllables  he  accentuated  the  odd- 
numbered  members  of  the  series.  In  other  words,  the  effect 
of  his  intent  was  of  such  magnitude  as  to  give  rise  to  the 
paradoxical  result  that  a  trochaic  learning  is  accomplished 
by  means  of  an  iambic  reading. 

Not  only,  then,  is  the  intent  a  potent  factor  in  the  work 
of  establishing  associations  between  mental  contents;  its 
influence  is  perhaps  even  more  clearly  manifested  in  the 
subsequent  coming  into  operation  of  these  associations. 
Associative  bonds  seldom  exist  in  one-to-one  form.  In  con 
sequence  of  his  many  years  of  experience,  an  intricate  net 
work  of  associations  and  inter-associations  comes  to  be 
established  among  the  various  mental  contents  of  every 
adult.  Each  datum  of  experience  is  associatively  connected 
not  with  a  single  other  content  but  with  hosts  of  other  con 
tents.  And  this  multiplicity  of  associative  bonds  is  a  de 
sideratum,  since  it  conduces  to  definiteness  of  meaning  and 
clearness  of  understanding.  But  if  the  associative  mechan 
ism  were  the  sole  determinant  of  mental  functioning,  as 
certain  psychologists  have  held,  this  very  complexity  of 

1  When  the  method  of  paired  associates  is  to  be  employed,  the  materials 
to  be  learned  are  presented  in  pairs;  then  the  test  of  retention  consists 
in  the  experimenter's  presenting  the  first  member  of  any  pair,  the  learner 
being  required  to  reproduce  the  second  member  of  the  pair. 


314  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

mental  associates  would  result  in  mental  incompetence. 
The  associative  bond  which  at  any  given  moment  is  most 
ready  to  come  into  operation  would  inevitably  come  into 
operation;  and  the  corresponding  idea,  however  relevant  or 
irrelevant,  would  thereupon  be  thrust  into  consciousness. 
Then,  too,  in  cases  where  two  or  more  associative  bonds 
were  present  in  equal  or  approximately  equal  strength,  they 
would  all  tend  to  come  into  operation  simultaneously;  asso 
ciative  inhibition  would  inevitably  result  and  mental  ac 
tivity  would  come  to  a  standstill.  In  the  former  case,  wealth 
of  mental  associates  would  conduce  to  irrelevance  and  redin 
tegration;  in  the  latter  case  it  would  conduce  to  a  suspension 
of  mental  activity. 

In  view  of  the  multiplicity  of  mental  associates,  it  is  indis 
pensable  that,  if  the  mental  mechanism  is  to  function  effi 
ciently,  the  process  of  selecting  that  associative  bond  which 
shall  come  into  operation  in  any  given  case  shall  not  be 
determined  by  the  fortuitous  circumstance  of  greatest  as 
sociative  strength  at  that  particular  instant.  And  as  a  mat 
ter  of  fact,  it  is  the  intent  which  frees  us  from  the  fetters  of 
associative  bondage,  because  it  is  one's  momentary  purpose 
or  attitude  which  determines  what  selection  shall  be  made 
from  among  the  numerous  mental  associates  which  are 
available  in  any  given  case. 

For  instance,  in  the  association  experiment  the  experi 
menter  gives  the  instructions:  "I  am  going  to  present  the 
name  of  a  country,  and  you  are  to  respond  with  the  name 
of  its  capital;"  he  then  presents  the  name  "England"  and 
the  reagent  responds  with  the  word  "London."  In  a  second 
case  the  instructions  are:  "I  am  going  to  present  the  name 
of  a  country,  and  you  are  to  respond  with  the  name  of  its 
most  important  river;"  here,  when  "England"  is  presented, 
the  response  is  "Thames."  In  a  third  case  the  instructions 
are:  "I  am  going  to  present  the  name  of  a  country,  and  you 
are  to  respond  with  the  name  of  its  form  of  government;" 
here,  on  "England"  being  presented,  the  response  is  "Mon 
archy."  In  a  fourth  case  the  instructions  are:  "I  am  going 
to  present  the  name  of  a  country,  and  you  are  to  respond  with 


THE  ROLE  OF  INTENT  IN  MENTAL  FUNCTIONING         315 

the  name  of  its  most  noted  dramatist;"  here,  on  "England" 
being  presented,  the  reagent  responds  "Shakespeare."  And 
in  a  fifth  case  the  instructions  are:  "I  am  going  to  present 
the  name  of  a  country,  and  you  are  to  respond  with  the 
name  of  one  of  its  universities;"  here,  on  "England"  being 
presented,  the  response  is  "Oxford."  What,  now,  is  the 
reason  why  in  the  first  case  the  reagent  reproduced  only  the 
word  "London"  and  did  not  reproduce,  or  even  tend  to 
reproduce,  "Thames,"  or  "Monarchy,"  or  "Shakespeare," 
or  "Oxford,"  in  response  to  the  stimulus-word  "England?" 
From  the  fact  that  the  five  response-words  are  different  it 
is  obvious  that  at  least  five  ideas  have  become  associated, 
in  the  mind  of  the  reagent,  with  the  name  "England."  How 
are  we  to  explain  this  fact  of  selective  response, — the  fact, 
namely,  that  but  a  single  one  of  the  various  possible  asso 
ciations  came  into  operation  in  each  case?  This  remarkable 
diversity  (and  appropriateness)  of  selective  response  can 
only  be  accounted  for  in  terms  of  the  diversified  intent,  or 
purpose,  or  attitude  of  the  reagent;  and  of  the  consequent 
diversity  in  degree  of  functional  preparedness  of  the  various 
associative  bonds  concerned.  Moreover,  this  diversity  and 
appropriateness  of  selective  response  seems  to  represent  the 
type  of  functioning  which  is  fundamental  to  all  consistent, 
coherent,  and  constructive  thinking. 

But  for  the  influence  of  this  factor,  controlled  and  selective 
thinking  would  be  impossible.  Instead  of  sticking  to  his 
subject  the  thinker  would  wander  into  countless  irrelevancies, 
because  he  would  at  every  moment  be  a  prey  to  that  asso 
ciation  which  chanced  at  that  moment  to  be  functionally 
most  efficient.  The  pathological  phenomenon  which  is 
known  as  'flight  of  ideas'  furnishes  an  illustration  of  the 
rambling  which  is  characteristic  of  every  ideational  train 
which  is  not  directed  and  guided  by  an  intent.  And  on  the 
other  hand,  obsessions  illustrate  the  type  of  ideational  train 
whose  course  is  determined  and  directed  by  a  permanently 
immutable  intent. 

The  mechanism  by  means  of  which  this  'intentional'  in 
fluence  is  exerted  and  controlled  has  not  yet  been  sufficiently 


316  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

investigated.  That  the  phenomenon  is  volitional  in  its 
essential  character  there  can  be  no  doubt;  indeed,  there 
seems  every  reason  to  identify  the  intent  with  a  phase  of  the 
volitional  process,  and  hence  to  believe  that  coherent  think 
ing  is  at  bottom  quite  as  much  volitional  as  it  is  intellectual. 
Ach  and  others  have  shown  that,  temporally,  the  intent 
belongs  to  the  fore-period, — that  is,  that  its  advent  is  an 
terior  to  the  process  of  attacking  the  problem  in  hand  or 
attempting  to  accomplish  the  task  in  question.  Although 
Ach  has  done  pioneer  service  in  emphasizing  the  significance 
of  the  Aujgdbe,  he  has  thrown  no  light  upon  its  modus 
operandi.  Two  envisagements  of  the  mechanism  have  been 
advocated.  Ach  conceives  that  it  operates  as  a  vis  a  tergo; 
others  conceive  it  as  a  force  which  attracts  from  in  front 
rather  than  as  a  force  which  impels  from  behind.  According 
to  Ach,  the  task  which  is  accepted  during  the  fore-period 
determines  and  directs  the  course  of  the  train  of  ideas  which 
follows  in  its  wake.  According  to  the  view  of  AschafFenburg, 
Meumann,  and  others,  the  task  exerts  its  influence  in  in 
direct  fashion;  it  gives  rise  directly  to  the  setting  up  of  a 
goal-idea,  and  this  in  turn  attracts  the  ideational  train 
toward  it. 

Several  genetic  stages  may  be  differentiated  in  the  intent. 
At  the  outset,  at  its  earliest  genetic  stage,  the  intent  is  ini 
tiated  by  a  definite  process  of  volition;  and  during  this  stage 
the  intent  is  clearly  and  definitely  present  to  consciousness. 
In  the  course  of  time,  however,  in  consequence  of  its  being 
frequently  initiated,  its  conscious  representation  becomes 
gradually  more  vague  and  indefinite,  until  finally  it  no  longer 
exists  as  a  datum  of  consciousness.  In  its  later  stages,  there 
fore,  the  presence  of  the  intent  can  only  be  inferred  from  the 
fact  that  its  results  are  manifestly  present.  What  was  at 
the  outset  a  volitional  and  deliberate  and  conscious  intent 
has  now  become  an  habitual  attitude  or  a  customary  point 
of  view.  Yet  the  functioning  at  this  ultimate  stage  is  no  less 
effective  and  facile  than  at  any  of  its  earlier  stages.  In 
cases  of  doubt  or  difficulty,  however,  where  one  is  confronted 
by  a  novel  task  or  an  intricate  problem,  the  automatized 


THE  ROLE  OF  INTENT  IN  MENTAL  FUNCTIONING         317 

and  mechanized  type  of  functioning  no  longer  suffices.  One's 
only  recourse  is  to  initiate  an  appropriate  intent,  and  to 
envisage  it  in  such  definitely  conscious  fashion  as  shall  insure 
its  successful  functioning  in  the  novel  or  intricate  situation 
where  selective  reaction  of  a  highly  complex  and  differenti 
ated  sort  is  imperative  and  where  automatized  and  mechan 
ized  functioning  proves  to  be  ineffective. 

It  is  difficult  in  the  present  status  of  neurological  knowl 
edge  to  envisage  the  details  of  a  neural  mechanism  which 
could  serve  to  make  it  possible  that  intent  and  attitude  may 
be  capable  of  so  profoundly  influencing  (neural  and)  mental 
functioning.  The  phenomena  revealed  by  the  complication 
experiment  and  by  the  simple  reaction  experiment, — the 
phenomenon,  namely,  that  one  may  at  will  bring  this  or  that 
impression  more  promptly  to  consciousness,  and  the  phe 
nomenon  that  one  may  at  will  react  either  more  promptly  or 
more  discriminatingly  (in  muscular  or  in  sensory  fashion), — 
these  and  other  phenomena  of  analogous  character  have  long 
since  shown  us  that  nerve  conduction  may  be  accelerated, 
retarded,  inhibited,  diverted,  or  otherwise  modified  by 
purely  subjective  factors.  Hence  there  is  nothing  unique  in 
the  hypothesis  that  the  mere  act  of  willing,  of  intending,  or 
of  assuming  an  attitude  may  somehow  serve  to  throw  a 
synaptic  switch  into  the  position  which  is  momentarily  ap 
propriate;  that  by  thus  setting  the  switch  in  any  given  posi 
tion  one  may  guide  the  ideational  train  in  any  desired  direc 
tion;  and  that  in  consequence  of  being  repeatedly  set  in  a 
given  position  the  switch  may  tend  not  only  to  assume  that 
position  more  readily  but  also  to  remain  in  that  position  more 
permanently. 


THE  RELATION  OF  PUNISHMENT  TO 
DISAPPROBATION 

THEODORE  DE  LACUNA 

IT  is  too  much  to  expect  from  the  frankest  of  physicians 
that  he  should  give  us  a  candid  criticism  of  the  practice  of 
medicine  as  it  exists  today.  But  he  has  no  scruples  against 
telling  us  how  ignorant  and  often  harmful  it  was  a  generation 
or  two  ago.  The  profession  then  still  retained  a  naive  faith 
in  the  virtues  of  various  drugs  as  'cures'  for  various  diseases, 
which  later  investigation  has  not  justified.  Outside  the 
profession,  indeed,  the  use  of  dangerous  household  remedies 
and  patent  medicines  prevailed  almost  unchecked.  Our 
fathers,  and  even  more  our  grandfathers,  were  dosed  with 
physic,  upon  the  slightest  excuse,  to  an  extent  that  seems 
appalling,  until  it  is  suggested  that  the  endurance  which  they 
displayed  is  a  most  convincing  evidence  of  the  toughness 
of  our  stock.  If  it  could  stand  that,  it  can  stand  pretty 
nearly  anything. 

So  the  genial  monitor  of  our  homes  now  informs  us;  and 
he  even  goes  so  far  as  to  say  that  the  fewer  prescriptions 
he  writes  the  better  he  earns  his  fee.  If,  then,  we  turn  upon 
him  and  ask  how,  among  a  civilized  and  enlightened  people, 
the  belief  in  drugs  could  so  long  persist,  he  answers,  first, 
that  no  doubt  the  drugs  did  sometimes  do  substantial  good; 
and,  secondly,  that,  as  most  men  would  recover  from  most 
diseases  without  medical  assistance,  they  will  also  generally 
recover  unless  the  drugs  they  take  are  decidedly  injurious 
to  them;  so  that  almost  any  drug  can  show  a  handsome 
percentage  of  cures.  Besides,  when  a  man  was  sick,  to  whom 
could  he  turn  if  not  to  the  physician;  and  to  what  could  the 
physician  turn  if  not  to  his  drugs?  Something,  it  was  felt, 
had  to  be  done.  It  was  easy,  like  Moliere  and  Rousseau,  to 
talk  against  physic;  but  what  could  they  put  in  its  place? 


PUNISHMENT  AND  DISAPPROBATION  319 

What  the  practice  of  medicine  was  a  generation  or  two 
ago,  such  is  punishment  as  it  is  administered  in  our  homes 
and  in  our  penal  institutions  today.  I  do  not  mean  to  say 
that  punishment  is  upon  the  whole  a  bad  thing;  and  I  am 
far  from  wishing  to  suggest  its  abolition.  But  it  appears  to 
me  that  it  is  administered  with  as  little  real  knowledge  of 
its  possible  or  probable  effects  as  our  forebears  had  of  the 
virtues  of  the  dark-brown  doses  which  they  prescribed  and 
swallowed.  The  situation  is  precisely  analogous.  A  wrong 
has  been  committed  and  something  must  be  done.  You  and 
I  were  punished  when  we  were  young,  and  behold  us  now! 
If  we  had  been  punished  a  little  more  frequently  and  severely, 
perhaps  it  would  have  been  better  for  us.  The  sensible  men 
of  old  imprisoned  and  hanged  criminals;  and  society  is  pre 
served  to  us.  If  they  had  imprisoned  and  hanged  a  few 
more,  so  much  the  more  stable  our  social  institutions  might 
be.  And,  as  the  physician  could  always  point  with  impres 
sive  effect  to  the  unfortunates  who  had  despised  his  ministra 
tions  and  had  died  in  consequence;  so  the  parent  and  the 
judge  can  point  to  many  a  culprit  who  has  been  spared  the 
lash,  and  who  has  grown  up  in  iniquity  and  social  rebellion. 

Very  curious  has  been  the  attitude  of  moral  philosophy 
toward  punishment.  Except  on  the  part  of  a  comparatively 
few  radical  skeptics,  the  assumption  has  been  made  that 
punishment  is,  of  course,  on  the  whole  efficient  in  accom 
plishing  its  purpose.  There  has  been  some  disagreement 
as  to  whether  punishment  is  good  or  bad  for  the  individual 
punished;  but  its  utility  to  society  has  been  acknowledged 
without  hesitation.  The  question  has  been:  What  is  this 
utility?  Why  is  punishment  right?  or,  at  best:  On  what 
principles  can  it  be  most  effectively  administered?  The 
philosopher,  like  the  man  in  the  street,  has  had  a  faith  in 
punishment  altogether  comparable  to  the  old-fashioned  faith 
in  drugs.  The  broader  question,  whether  there  are  not  other 
agencies  that  can  accomplish  all  or  most  of  what  is  expected 
from  punishment,  and  accomplish  it  with  more  certainty 
and  with  less  incidental  loss,  has  not  only  been  generally 
neglected,  but  even  been  set  aside  as  foolish  or  wicked. 


320  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

I  do  not  now  propose  to  enter  into  a  discussion  of  the  va 
rious  theories  of  punishment.  My  former  pupil,  now  my 
colleague,  Dr.  A.  L.  Kellogg,  is  about  to  publish  an  important 
study  of  that  subject;  and  I  could  say  little  or  nothing  about 
it  that  I  have  not  learned  from  her.  I  shall  take  for  granted 
that  the  rationalistic  dogma  of  a  peculiar  a  priori  appropriate 
ness  of  punishment  to  crime  is  a  delusion;  that  the  juristic 
theory  of  deterrence  is  inadequate,  because,  except  where 
an  indiscriminate  'frightfulness'  is  practiced,  punishment 
does  not  effectually  deter;  that  the  humanitarian  theory  of 
reformation  is  inadequate,  because,  generally  speaking, 
punishment  has  no  direct  reformatory  influence;  and  that 
the  real  value  of  punishment  is,  for  the  most  part,  as  one 
means  among  others  whereby  the  sentiment,  or  attitude,  of 
respect  for  authority  is  fostered, — by  no  means  always  the 
best  means,  sometimes  useless,  sometimes  indispensable.  As 
such,  I  shall  assume,  punishment  does  important  service  in 
maintaining  domestic  and  civil  peace  and  order,  and  thus 
helps  to  ensure  the  necessary  conditions  under  which  the 
development  of  good  character  takes  place.  I  dare  say  there 
will  be  few  readers  that  will  not  be  willing  to  concede  all  this. 

But  the  altered  views  of  the  function  and  value  of  punish 
ment  that  are  now  prevalent  among  us,  suggest  an  over 
hauling  of  our  notions  of  the  relation  of  punishment  to  moral 
disapprobation.  Is  Westermarck,  for  example,  right  in  main 
taining  that  approbation  and  disapprobation  are  essentially 
retributive  emotions,  belonging  thus  to  the  same  general  class 
as  anger  and  gratitude,  and,  in  particular,  that  disappro 
bation  is  a  species  of  resentment?  And  is  he,  accordingly, 
further  right  in  maintaining  that  punishment  is  simply  an 
overt  expression  of  more  or  less  intense  moral  disapproba 
tion,  the  severity  of  the  punishment  being  in  general  an 
index  of  the  intensity  of  the  disapprobation?  It  appears  to 
me  that  he  is  clearly  and  demonstrably  wrong. 

I.  Students  of  ethics  everywhere  are  so  deeply  indebted  to 
Westermarck  for  the  immense  array  of  detailed  facts  which 
he  has  gathered  and  arranged  for  their  benefit,  that  to  point 
out  a  neglected  field  may  well  seem  ungrateful.  The  fact 


PUNISHMENT  AND  DISAPPROBATION  321 

remains  that  there  are  wide  and  important  categories  of  moral 
ideas  which  his  treatment  has  left  almost  entirely  untouched; 
and,  if  I  am  not  mistaken,  his  general  theory  has  suffered 
seriously  in  consequence. 

It  is  noteworthy,  for  example,  that  in  his  two  bulky 
volumes  the  virtue  of  courage  is  only  incidentally  mentioned. 
And  yet  nothing  is  more  characteristic  of  the  morality  of  a 
people  than  their  notion  of  courage.  Courage  may  be  recog 
nized  in  insensibility  to  pain  and  danger,  in  joyous  enthusi 
asm,  in  confident  superiority,  in  ferocity,  in  desperation,  in 
grim  determination,  or  in  a  sweet  serenity;  and  where  one 
sees  courage  another  sees  brutishness  or  fanaticism  or  even 
outright  cowardice.  The  Stoic  emperor  saw  no  courage  in 
the  Christian  martyrs.  The  American  soldiers  saw  no  cour 
age  in  the  ' treacherous'  Filipinos.  German  soldiers  have 
gleefully  told  of  their  success  in  using  non-combatants  as 
a  shield.  Was  this  cowardice? 

Similarly,  Westermarck  has  nothing  to  say  in  any  sys 
tematic  way  with  regard  to  the  virtue  of  temperance,  though 
that  too  has  undergone  some  surprising  modifications.  It 
may  be  indifference  to  a  particular  temptation  or  to  the 
common  sources  of  illicit  pleasure.  It  may  be  the  modera 
tion  of  good  taste.  It  may  be  egoistic  prudence.  It  may 
be  the  self-denial  of  extreme  asceticism. 

He  has  nothing  to  say  of  the  virtue  of  wisdom,  whether  it 
be  the  experience  and  common  sense  of  Nestor,  the  craft  of 
Ulysses,  the  political  foresight  of  Solon,  the  self-analysis  of 
Socrates,  or  the  philosophical  insight  of  Plato, — to  choose 
only  a  few  illustrations  from  the  developing  standards  of  a 
single  people. 

2.  And  now  let  it  be  observed  that  cowardice,  intem 
perance,  and  folly  are  generally  unpunished.  There  are,  to 
be  sure,  conditions  under  which  the  punishment  follows. 
Cowardice  in  battle,  for  example,  when  it  leads  to  a  distinct 
dereliction  of  duty,  may  be  severely  punished.  But  cow 
ardice  that  does  not  lead  to  crime  generally  goes  scot-free, 
no  matter  how  ignoble  it  may  be.  The  like  is  true  of  intem 
perance,  and,  more  generally,  of  all  lack  of  self-control. 


322  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

Drunkenness  is  punished  when  it  leads  to  disorderliness,  or 
when  it  occurs  in  a  place  where  the  mere  exhibition  of  it  is 
regarded  as  an  infraction  of  the  public  order.  The  soldier 
who  sleeps  at  his  post  is  shot,  not  because  he  lacks  self- 
control,  but  because  he  has  slept  at  his  post.  And  it  goes 
without  saying  that  no  one  is  punished  simply  for  being  a 
fool. 

It  may  be  added  that  the  moral  faults  comprehended  under 
the  name  of  ' selfishness'  are  generally  unpunished.  Avarice, 
though  it  be  plainly  vicious,  is  safe  so  long  as  it  keeps  within 
the  law.  Lack  of  public  spirit  or  of  love  of  country  is  not 
punished.  Even  cruelty,  though  it  rouses  protective  sym 
pathy  and  anger,  is  often  beyond  the  range  of  punitive 
measures. 

These  facts  may  be  summed  up  in  the  statement  that,  in 
general,  the  only  moral  standards  that  are  enforced  by  means 
of  punishment  are  the  standards  of  duty, — not  those  of  vir 
tuous  character  or  of  benevolent  intention.  But  it  is  not 
even  the  case  that  all  standards  of  duty  are  enforced  by 
punishment.  Lying  is  generally  unpunished,  even  when  it 
is  extremely  shameful;  though  perjury  is  punished  very 
severely.  The  most  shocking  disregard  of  a  father's  duties 
is  rarely  punishable.  Inhospitality  may  be  punished  by  the 
gods  above,  but  not  by  men  below. 

What  then  is  punished?  Non-submission  to  authority; 
that  is  to  say,  disobedience  either  to  the  commands  of  a 
superior  or  to  the  law  of  the  land. 

3.  It  may  be  objected,  that  serious  breaches  of  custom 
are  punished,  where  no  law  in  the  proper  sense  of  the  term 
exists.  That  is  true,  if  ' punishment'  is  given  a  sufficiently 
wide  denotation.  I  do  not  care  to  attempt  a  definition  in 
this  place;  not  because  a  tenable  definition  would  not  be 
useful,  but  because  an  elaborate  discussion  would  be  neces 
sary  in  order  to  prove  its  tenability.  It  is  simpler  to  point 
to  the  nature  of  those  primitive  practices  which  may  be 
called  'punishment.'  In  the  first  place,  revenge  exists, — as 
it  does  even  in  certain  of  the  higher  animals, — and  a  crowd, 
whether  of  savages  or  of  civilized  men,  may  be  at  least  as 


PUNISHMENT  AND  DISAPPROBATION  323 

angry  and  revengeful  as  an  individual.  When  a  whole  com 
munity  is  roused  to  revenge,  the  action  may  be  difficult  to 
distinguish  from  a  punishment.  In  the  second  place,  the 
need  for  purification  from  the  pollution  of  guilt,  and  for  the 
appeasing  of  offended  deities,  exists;  and  because  pollution 
is  contagious,  and  the  anger  of  the  gods,  too,  is  liable  to 
attach  not  simply  to  the  offender  but  to  all  who  are  connected 
with  him,  purification  and  atonement  easily  become  com 
munal  concerns.  If,  then,  by  washing  or  burning  or  exiling 
a  man  and  his  family,  a  grave  danger  can  be  averted  from 
the  larger  group,  the  whole  group  will  very  naturally  take 
a  hand  in  seeing  that  this  precaution  is  taken;  or,  if  there 
are  special  functionaries  entrusted  with  the  magical  or  re 
ligious  welfare  of  the  community,  these  may  well  take  upon 
themselves  the  performance  of  the  necessary  rites.  Such 
action  also  may  be  regarded  as  punishment,  if  the  means  of 
purification  or  atonement  involve  the  infliction  of  pain  or 
loss  upon  the  guilty  party. 

Apart  from  such  exceptions,  the  principle  which  is  stated 
above, — that  only  non-submission  to  authority  is  pun 
ished, — is,  I  believe,  generally  valid. 

4.  I  should  like  in  this  place  to  make  a  suggestion  with 
regard  to  the  historical  origin  of  punishment.  Does  it  spring, 
as  has  been  widely  held,  from  revenge,  as  appears,  for  ex 
ample,  in  the  case  of  the  cessation  of  the  blood-feud?  The 
appearance,  I  think,  is  deceptive.  Blood-revenge  does  not 
grow  into  punishment.  On  the  contrary,  it  is  suppressed 
largely  by  means  of  punishment,  and  punishment  takes  its 
place.  I  can  find  no  evidence  of  any  real  continuity  in  the 
alleged  development.  Or  does  punishment  arise  from  rites 
of  purification?  Is  chastisement,  as  the  Socrates  of  the 
Gorgias  conceived  it,  essentially  a  means  of  freeing  the  soul 
from  the  evil  of  iniquity?  I  can  urge  but  little  against  such 
a  view,  except  that  there  is  little  or  nothing  to  be  urged  for 
it.  The  plain  fact,  it  appears  to  me,  is  that  the  rise  of  punish 
ment  is  part  and  parcel  of  the  rise  of  authority:  the  authority 
of  chiefs,  of  heads  of  households,  of  gods,  and  of  states.  The 
punishment,  by  new-born  states,  of  deeds  of  violence  that 


324  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

have  hitherto  been  held  in  check  only  by  revenge,  is  simply 
a  case  in  point. 

If  the  inquiry  be  pushed  back  a  step  and  the  origin  of 
authority  itself  be  sought,  a  partial  answer, — perhaps  the 
most  significant  part  of  a  complete  answer, — is  that  it  arises 
from  the  increased  necessity  of  co-operation  in  work.    This 
is,  of  course,  Rousseau's  great  sociological  principle:  "Corn 
and  iron  have  enslaved  the  human  race."     Where,  for  ex 
ample,  children  do  not  work  under  the  direction  of  their 
elders,  the  latter  feel  little  desire  to  assert  authority  over 
them  and  seldom  punish  them.    Under  such  circumstances,  a 
parent  may,  on  occasion,  get  terribly  exasperated  at  his 
child, — though  even  this  is  rare, — and  strike  him  brutally 
in  consequence.     But  he  has,  in  general,  no  commands  to 
give  him;  the  child  lives  his  own  life,  except  as  he  comes  to 
the  women  for  food;  and  as  there  is  little  authority  to  be 
enforced,  there  is  little  enforcement  of  it.     Similarly,  the 
authority  of  tribal  chiefs  is  no  doubt  mainly  due  to  the  ne 
cessity  of  effective  co-operation  in  war.     It  may  be  limited 
to  periods  of  actual  war.    Whether  temporary  or  permanent, 
it  must  be  actively  exerted;  and  thus  punishment  is  involved. 
What,  then,  is  the  primitive  motive  of  punishment?    The 
resentment  of  the  superior  at  not  being  obeyed.    There  is  no 
project  of  reformation.     Among  people  of  a  low  grade  of 
culture  there  is  surely  no  project  of  deterrence;  that  belongs 
to  a  reflective  theory.    On  the  other  hand,  the  actual  effect 
of  punishment  is  not  simply  to  compel  obedience.     Obe 
dience  may,  within  a  very  limited  range  of  conditions,  be 
compelled  by  torture.    But  more  than  this  is  required;  and 
more  than  this  is  in  general  secured  without  anything  ap 
proaching  torture;  namely,  the  conscious  duty  of  obedience. 
The  superior  punishes  because  he  feels  that  he  ought  to  have 
been  obeyed.     The  punishment  has  the  moral  support,  as 
well  as  perhaps  the  physical  support,  of  the  community. 
And  the  culprit  feels  not  only  the  physical  blows,  but  also 
their  significance.     To   the  question,   therefore,   what  the 
primitive  function  of  punishment  is,  I  would  answer:  Pre 
cisely  what  its  proper  function  to-day  is.     It  is  one  of  the 


•PUNISHMENT  AND  DISAPPROBATION  325 

agencies  through  which  willing  submission  to  authority  is 
secured. 

It  is  worth  notice  that  in  early  society  there  is  no  specific 
duty  of  punishment.  It  is  a  right.  If  the  superior  wishes  to 
pardon,  he  does  so  without  committing  any  injustice;  just 
as,  generally  speaking,  an  injured  man  does  no  injustice  if 
he  fails  to  revenge  himself  on  his  enemy.  Such  a  conception 
sometimes  persists,  especially  where  there  is  an  autocratic 
government,  to  an  advanced  stage  of  culture.  The  good- 
natured  caliph,  on  the  occasion  of  his  marriage  to  a  fourth 
wife,  or  of  the  birth  to  him  of  an  heir  to  the  throne,  sets  free 
a  multitude  of  jail-birds;  and  the  people  applaud  his  clem 
ency.  Punishment  may  become  a  duty  through  custom.  It 
necessarily  becomes  so,  when  the  officer  who  directs  it  acts 
as  the  servant  of  a  God  or  of  an  earthly  sovereign;  and  this 
happens  equally  when,  through  reflective  thought,  punish 
ment  comes  to  be  regarded  as  a  means  of  fulfilling  various 
responsibilities  which  custom  has  laid  upon  husband,  parent, 
master,  or  sovereign.  "Spare  the  rod,  and  spoil  the  child/' 
is,  of  course,  in  the  first  instance,  a  prudential  maxim:  if 
you  want  children  that  are  worth  having  you  must  beat 
them  into  form.  But  let  a  responsibility  for  moral  education 
arise,  so  that  the  community  looks  to  the  parent  to  "train 
up  a  child  in  the  way  he  should  go,"  and  then  chastisement 
is  a  duty  that  is  owed  either  to  the  community  or  to  the 
family  or  to  the  child  himself.  In  this  case  punishment  may 
go  beyond  its  primitive  and  normal  limits.  Since  it  is  sup 
posed  to  improve  the  child,  any  moral  fault  may  be  regarded 
as  calling  for  it:  cowardice  or  meanness,  for  example.  Yet 
even  here,  I  think,  most  men  would  hesitate.  It  is  impos 
sible,  they  would  say,  by  means  of  penalties,  to  make  chil 
dren  brave  and  generous. 

Enough  has  been  said,  I  think,  to  show  that  punishment 
is  not  essentially  an  expression  of  moral  disapprobation  as 
such.  There  are  important  classes  of  adverse  moral  judg 
ments  that  seldom  issue  in  punishment;  and  when  punish 
ment  is  inflicted  it  is  not,  as  a  rule,  for  a  moral  offense 
sitnpliciUr,  but  for  insubordination. 


326  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

5.  What,  then,  shall  we  say  of  the  attitude  of  moral  dis 
approbation  itself?  Is  it  one  of  hostility  or  resentment? 
Undoubtedly  it  may  be;  but  also  undoubtedly  it  need  not  be, 
and  generally  is  not.  An  exhibition  of  cowardice  arouses 
contempt,  in  extreme  cases  even  loathing.  The  coward  is 
jeered  at;  men  shrink  from  contact  with  him,  as  if  he  were  of 
some  despised  lower  race.  But  of  resentment  there  is  none, 
unless  on  the  ground  of  particular  offenses  into  which  his 
cowardice  has  led  him.  The  like  is  true  of  the  intemperate 
man  and  of  the  fool.  And  the  like  is  also  true  of  the  offender 
against  many  of  the  standards  of  duty.  To  be  caught  in  a 
lie  is  a  shame  and  disgrace.  That  is  enough,  perhaps;  but, 
at  any  rate,  it  is  all, — unless,  indeed,  the  lie  is  itself  a  means 
of  further  injustice  or  a  case  of  insubordination.  Even  where 
the  offense  against  duty  is  one  that  distinctly  calls  for  pun 
ishment,  it  by  no  means  follows  that  in  all  who  condemn  the 
fault  there  is  a  feeling  of  resentment  against  the  culprit. 

The  phenomena  of  self-condemnation  are  here  of  especial 
significance.  When  the  moral  sentiments  are  regarded  as 
essentially  retributive,  their  direction  toward  the  self  is 
necessarily  conceived  as  a  secondary  development.  Now  I 
would  not  deny  that  states  occur  which  may  fairly  be  de 
scribed  as  moral  resentment  against  oneself;  for  example, 
the  feeling  that  one  ought  to  be  severely  punished,  not  be 
cause  punishment  is  a  good,  but  because  one  has  deserved 
ill.  Under  such  circumstances  a  man  may  proceed  to  impose 
a  penalty  upon  himself  very  much  as  a  stern  judge  might 
do.  But  surely  this  is  not  the  usual  type  of  self- 
condemnation.  As  the  attitude  toward  another  is  less  often 
one  of  resentment  than  one  of  contempt,  so  the  attitude 
toward  oneself  is  far  less  often  one  of  self-antagonism  than 
one  of  shame. 

It  may  be  urged  that  anger  and  resentment  are  older  than 
contempt  and  shame.  And  doubtless  so  they  are;  but  they 
are  all  older  than  morality.  The  moral  sentiments  in  their 
development  were  thus  quite  as  free  to  grow  upon  the  latter 
stock  as  upon  the  former.  And  there  is  indirect  evidence  to 
show  that  moral  contempt  and  shame  are  at  least  as  old  as 


PUNISHMENT  AND  DISAPPROBATION  327 

moral  resentment.  Neither  the  civilized  man  nor  the  savage 
passes  moral  judgments  upon  anyone  whom  he  does  not 
credit  with  a  capacity  of  passing  moral  judgments  upon 
himself.  The  self-judgment,  therefore,  can  hardly  be  re 
garded  as  a  secondary  outgrowth  of  the  judgment  upon 
another.  The  two  have  most  assuredly  developed  together. 
The  application  of  the  foregoing  remarks  to  moral  appro 
bation  is  obvious. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION: 

A  CRITIQUE 

EDWARD  L.  SCHAUB 

To  characterize  modern  thought  and  civilization  as  scien 
tific  is  to  imply  that  the  dominating  interest  is  fundamentally 
practical.  For  even  where  the  concern  is  not  with  invention 
and  machinery,  with  a  search  for  methods  in  the  direct  in 
terests  of  control,  or  with  the  utilization  of  scientific  laws  in 
the  achievement  of  human  purposes,  the  orientation  of  the 
scientific  is  towards  the  practical.  This  fact,  it  is  true,  is 
one  of  which  the  devotee  of  so-called  'pure  science'  is  some 
times  unaware.  He  may,  indeed,  repel  as  an  affront  the 
claim  that  his  efforts,  beyond  those  of  all  other  men  perhaps, 
are  directed  fundamentally  and  constantly  by  the  demands 
of  human  life  upon  the  physical  and  the  social  environment. 
But  if  there  is  one  thing  which  history  and  logic  substantiate, 
and  upon  which  widely  differing  philosophical  schools  may 
agree,  it  is  the  fact  that  the  underlying  motives  determinant 
of  the  presuppositions,  the  methods,  and  the  problems  of 
modern  science  are  essentially,  even  if  not  exclusively,  prac 
tical.  If,  therefore,  the  life  of  to-day  is  correctly  apprehended 
by  those  who  characterize  it  as  scientific,  if  our  social  ex 
perience  is  constructed  of  the  results  of  science  and  is  per 
meated  by  its  spirit,  we  need  not  be  surprised  to  learn  that 
the  central  values  and  the  religion  of  the  age  focus  on  achieve 
ment. 

Relatively  unfettered  by  firmly  established  tradition  and 
stimulated  by  the  opportunities  of  a  new  and  a  richly  en 
dowed  land,  it  is  Americans  especially  among  whom  this 
impulse  for  achievement  is  paramount.  In  this  country 
particularly  would  assent  be  spontaneously  given  to  a  psy 
chology  which  dethrones  intellect  and  gives  the  place  of  pre 
eminence  in  human  experience  to  volition.  Not  that  the 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  329 

displacement  of  rational  psychologies  by  voluntaristic  inter 
pretations  was  conditioned  by  the  peculiar  temper  of  modern 
interests  or  of  American  life.  The  latter  merely  give  what 
seems  the  clear  and  distinct  ring  of  genuineness  to  a  psy 
chology  whose  immediate  springs  are  to  be  found  elsewhere. 
The  influence  of  comparative  psychology,  the  analysis  of 
the  mental  development  of  the  individual  and  the  race, 
various  experimental  investigations,  the  phenomena  of  ab 
normality,  and  interpretation  of  social  actions, — all  have 
conspired  to  shift  the  psychological  emphasis  from  ideas, 
theories,  and  cognition  generally,  to  impulses,  instincts, 
desires,  habits,  emotional  dispositions,  and  valuational  atti 
tudes.  Supplementing  the  factors  that  have  brought  about 
this  change  were  potent  influences  emerging  from  evolu 
tionary  conceptions  and,  more  particularly,  from  biology 
itself.  In  certain  instances  these  latter  influences  were  far 
indeed  from  being  merely  auxiliary.  On  the  contrary,  they 
asserted  a  dominance,  subordinating  to  themselves  such 
tractable  facts  and  conclusions  as  otherwise  appeared,  and 
giving  their  own  particular  stamp  to  voluntarism  as  a  whole. 
Under  these  conditions  the  emphasis  came  to  be  placed  al 
most  exclusively  upon  the  practical.  The  mental  life  lost  its 
status  of  relative  independence  and  primacy.  It  was  dis 
possessed  of  any  ends  or  problems  of  its  own  setting  and 
regarded  as  an  expression  of  the  life-principle  of  physiological 
organisms.  Not  merely  was  conation  believed  to  be  the 
fundamental  characteristic  and  capacity  of  the  human  in 
dividual,  but  conation, — indeed,  mental  life  as  a  whole,— 
was  interpreted  as  "an  instrument  of  adaptation  by  which 
the  organism  adjusts  itself  to  the  environment."  1  Not 

1  Ames,  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  p.  15.  It  is  this  general 
principle  that  Ames  adopts  as  the  basis  of  his  account  of  religious  experi 
ence.  Four  facts,  however,  should  be  noted  with  reference  to  Ames's 
standpoint:  (i)  Mind  is  also  described  as  more  specific  in  function,  namely, 
as  "the  means  by  which  adaptations  occur  in  novel  and  complex  situa 
tions  "  (p.  15).  The  limitation  of  mind's  function  to  novel  and  complex 
situations,  however,  is  obviously  unwarranted  if,  as  Ames  does,  we  include 
within  the  concept  'mind'  instinctive  processes  (cf.  p.  16),  as  well  as 
desire,  habit,  and  emotion  (cf.  p.  303).  (2)  No  one  view  is  consistently 


330  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

merely  were  appreciative  and  valuating  attitudes  given  a 
priority  over  cognitive  interests,  but  they  were  held  to 
originate  in,  and  to  derive  their  sole  significance  from,  the 
stresses  and  strains,  the  embarrassments  and  the  difficulties, 
attending  the  demands  of  the  life-process  upon  a  more  or 
less  foreign  and  refractory  environment.1  The  psychologist, 
King  tells  us,  "should  attempt  to  treat  the  acts  and  states  of 
consciousness  with  reference  to  their  setting  and  function 
in  the  general  life-process."  2  According  to  the  functional 
position  thus  suggested,  even  the  most  complex  and  the  most 
valued  of  human  activities  are  ultimately  traceable  to  the 
needs  of  the  organism,  or,  at  any  rate,  to  simple  activities 
characteristic  of  the  initiative  (if  there  be  such)  and  the  re 
sponses  of  the  life-process.  Closely  dependent  upon  the 

adhered  to  regarding  the  relation  of  the  "instrument"  to  the  "organism" 
which  through  it  "adjusts  itself  to  the  environment."  The  passage  quoted 
implies  a  subordination  of  the  mind  to  the  organism;  in  other  connections, 
however,  it  is  the  latter  that  is  represented  as  secondary,  the  neural  ac 
tivity  and  the  objective  effects  being  said  to  express  or  to  register  the 
adjusting  activity  (p.  15).  (3)  Similarly,  the  reader  is  confused  by  an 
ambiguity  in  the  term  ( mind-body.'  At  the  outset,  a  *  mind-body' 
process  is  described  in  terms  of  a  relation  between  mental  and  bodily 
states  (p.  18);  somewhat  later  a  '  mind-body  '  process  is  interpreted  as  an 
activity  of  the  organism  (p.  20) ;  still  a  different  view  is  implied  when  the 
question,  "What  is  the  organism,  the  mind-body,  doing?"  is  followed  by 
the  sentence,  "In  other  words,  What  is  the  will,  or  purposeful  activity, 
accomplishing?"  (p.  20).  (4)  Ames  describes  the  adjustment  as  one  of  the 
organism  to  the  environment  (p.  15)  but  also  as  "an  adjustment  in  the 
psycho-physical  organism"  (p.  18),  and  still  again  as  one  which  occurs 
"through  the  psycho-physical  organism"  (p.  15).  In  the  opinion  of  the 
present  writer  the  various  ambiguities  and  inconsistencies  which  we  have 
mentioned  represent  not  mere  carelessness  or  accident;  they  are  outcrop- 
pings  of  serious  difficulties  that  inhere  in  the  adopted  standpoint. 

The  fourth  of  the  points  that  we  have  noted  is  mentioned  also  in  Pro 
fessor  Coe's  recent  Psychology  of  Religion  (p.  30,  note).  The  appearance 
of  this  volume  makes  it  necessary  to  say  that,  while  it  also  utilizes  in  part 
a  point  of  view  that  may  not  improperly  be  termed  'functional,'  the 
standpoint  is  radically  different  from  that  which  we  have  set  out  to  dis 
cuss  in  this  essay. 

1  The  standpoint  of  King  in  his  treatises,  The  Differentiation  of  the  Re 
ligious  Consciousness  and  The  Development  of  Religion. 

2  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  23. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  331 

various  activities,  simple  and  involved,  are  the  feelings  and 
sentiments  experienced  by  the  individual;  emerging  from 
them,  moreover,  as  plans  of  procedure  in  times  of  difficulty 
and  conflict,  are  ideas,  whose  very  significance,  therefore, 
is  determined  by  the  situations  that  generate  them,  whose 
importance  to  the  individual  is  conditioned  by  a  direct  per 
sonal  experience  of  the  obstacles  to  be  overcome,  and  whose 
validity  is  solely  a  matter  of  successful  guidance  in  practice. 

The  standpoint  thus  hastily  sketched  is,  of  course,  a 
matter  of  common  knowledge,  and  this  renders  it  super 
fluous  further  to  fill  in  the  details  of  the  outline.  In  many 
of  their  applications  and  developments,  moreover,  the  va 
rious  doctrines  involved  have  time  and  again  been  subjected 
to  criticism  and  have  in  turn  received  defense  or  restatement 
on  the  part  of  able  champions.  There  is  a  manifest  need, 
however,  for  further  appraisal,  as  concerning  more  specifically 
the  utilization  of  the  functional  principle  in  the  interpretation 
of  religious  experience.  True,  King,  Ames,  and  others  have, 
by  their  demonstrations  in  fact,  removed  from  the  region  of 
debate  the  question  as  to  whether  functionalism  may  offer 
any  genuine  contribution  to  our  knowledge  concerning  the 
origin,  nature,  and  development  of  religion.  The  very  im 
portance  of  their  discussions,  however,  promises  a  degree  of 
profitableness  to  one  who  seriously  questions  whether  the 
accounts  which  they  have  given  may  be  regarded  as  entirely 
successful. 

The  outstanding  characteristics  of  functional  interpreta 
tions  of  religion  and  the  features  that  have  contributed  most 
to  their  attractiveness  and  their  significance  are  perhaps 
three  in  number:  (I)  a  persistent  emphasis  on  the  volitional 
and,  more  particularly  still,  the  practical  character  of  re 
ligion,  as  well  as  on  the  intimacy  of  the  relation  between 
religion  and  life;  (II)  a  conviction  that  religion  may  be  under 
stood  only  through  a  study  of  its  development  and  of  the 
development  of  culture  as  a  whole, — hence  a  single-minded 
devotion  to  a  genetic  method  of  treatment;  (III)  a  recogni 
tion  of  the  essentially  social  character  of  religion,  as  regards 
origin  and  nature  as  well  as  development,  motives  as  well 


332  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

as  interests  and  ends.  Were  one  to  inquire  whether  a  func 
tional  standpoint  is  capable  of  furnishing  a  satisfactory 
account  of  religion,  many  far-reaching  questions  of  a  general 
nature  would  at  once  arise.  Is  a  functional  statement  cap 
able,  for  example,  of  giving  full  recognition  to  the  fact  and  the 
import  of  the  contemplative,  passive,  and  receptive  phases 
of  religion?  Can  it  provide  in  any  thorough-going  way  for 
the  insistence  of  the  religious  consciousness  that  its  object 
is  in  a  very  true  sense  both  transcendent  of  experience  and 
free  from  the  mutability  of  the  here  and  now?  Does  it 
enable  one  to  admit  that  religion  connotes,  not  so  much  ad 
justment  to  particular  situations  in  the  physical  or  social 
environment,  as  the  search  for  such  things  as  a  new  center 
of  experience,  a  deeper  life,  a  personal  appreciation  of  the 
value  and  meaning  of  reality,  or  an  identification  of  one's 
self  with  that  which  is  felt  to  be  alike  most  real  and  of  highest 
worth?  These  and  other  questions  are  of  serious  importance 
to  one  concerned  with  an  estimate  of  the  possibilities  and 
the  limitations  of  the  functional  standpoint  as  such.  Our 
present  purpose,  however,  is  of  a  more  restricted  scope.  We 
undertake  merely  an  examination  of  the  more  important 
accounts  of  religion  which  functionalism  has  thus  far  actually 
produced  and  we  further  restrict  our  discussion  to  three  sets 
of  considerations,  determined  by  those  features  of  functional 
interpretations  which  we  have  just  singled  out  as  most 
characteristic  and  significant. 

I 

To  the  man  of  common  sense  it  must  be  puzzling  to  under 
stand  how  even  eminent  writers, — among  them  psycholo 
gists, — could  come  to  define  religion  in  terms  of  some  idea  or 
set  of  ideas,  or  some  faculty  or  capacity  of  cognition.  Even  to 
the  most  superficial  glance,  if  only  it  be  naive,  religion  is  un 
mistakably  distinct  from  creeds  or  from  any  knowledge  about 
realities  or  facts;  individuals  and  peoples  to  whom  theories 
are  matters  of  utter  indifference  may  find  in  religion  that 
which  is  of  greatest  moment  to  them.  Now,  whatever  may 
be  the  particular  mental  bias  resulting  from  continuous  pre- 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  333 

occupation  with  functional  conceptions,  it  is  not  such  as 
readily  to  cause  a  confusion  between  religion  and  theory,  or 
any  undue  exaltation  of  the  role  of  ideas  in  religious  expe 
rience.  Not  cognition  or  even  emotion,  but  action,  is  felt  to 
constitute  the  inmost  being  of  religion,  as  of  life.  Hence  the 
emphasis  upon  custom,  ritual,  and  ceremony.  It  must  not 
be  inferred,  however,  that  the  functionalist  possesses  any 
peculiar  fondness  for  action  as  such;  rather  must  he  contend 
with  a  deep-seated  aversion  to  anything,  even  in  the  way 
of  action,  that  appears  from  the  point  of  view  of  utility 
as  superfluous.  As  keen  as  is  his  eye  to  detect  the  practical 
character  of  motives  and  results,  so  reluctant  is  his  disposi 
tion  to  admit  the  presence  or  the  worthwhileness  of  the 
unnecessary.  It  is  not  in  the  literature  of  functionalism, 
therefore,  that  the  beauty,  impressiveness,  and  sheer  inevi- 
tableness  of  ritual  receive  their  finest  portrayal.  Our  indebt 
edness  to  this  literature  is  connected  rather  with  our  present 
appreciation  of  the  extent  to  which  ritual  and  ceremony 
contribute  to  the  actual  needs  of  life. 

Merely  to  say  that,  for  the  functionalist,  religion  is  prima 
rily  an  attitude,  and  an  attitude  fundamentally  practical  in 
character,  is  not  as  yet  fully  to  define  his  conception.  All 
theorists  have  more  or  less  clearly  recognized  the  bearing  of 
religion  upon  life,  though,  of  course,  the  life  to  which  they 
have  referred  has  not  always  been  that  of  the  present  world 
or  that  of  the  socially-minded  individual.  There  has,  more 
over,  also  been  fairly  general  agreement  as  regards  the  con 
verse  fact.  Religion,  it  has  repeatedly  been  emphasized,  has 
been  profoundly  modified,  both  in  form  and  in  spirit,  by  the 
conditions  of  life,  the  nature  of  its  problems,  the  direction  of 
its  aspirations,  and  the  character  of  the  social,  economic,  and 
political  institutions  in  which  it  has  found  embodiment. 
Even  to  put  the  matter  thus,  however,  implies  a  dualism,  or 
at  least  a  distinction,  between  life  and  religion  which  the 
functionalist  seeks  to  avoid.  Says  King,  "Religious  beliefs 
and  practices  are  not  merely  modeled  upon  the  analogy  of  a 
people's  economic  and  social  life.  The  religious  life  is  this 
social  life  in  one  of  its  phases.  It  is  an  organic  part  of  the 


334  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

activity  of  the  social  body,  not  merely  something  built  upon 
it."  l 

The  contentions  both  of  the  essential  identity  of  religion 
with  life  in  one  of  its  phases  and  of  the  instrumental  char 
acter  of  religion  find  their  clearest  illustration  and  corrobora- 
tion  in  the  early  stages  of  culture.  It  is  to  these  especially, 
therefore,  that  functionalists  preferably  turn  and  it  is  with 
reference  to  them  that  their  interpretations  are  most  definite 
and  convincing.  Writes  King,  in  a  passage  which  Ames  has 
incorporated  in  one  of  his  chapters: 2  "Religion  in  primitive 
society  may  be  regarded  as  primarily  a  system  for  the  con 
trolling  of  the  group  with  reference  to  the  ends  which  are 
felt  most  acutely  by  the  group  as  a  group.  .  .  .  All  prac 
tices  designed  to  do  this  are  religious,  whether  they  are 
definite  forms  of  worship  or  not."  3  Quite  in  agreement  is 
the  view  of  Henke.  "A  rite  or  ceremony,"  he  tells  us,  "is 
the  observance  of  some  formal  act  or  series  of  acts  in  the 
manner  prescribed  by  custom  or  authority,  and  from  the 
point  of  view  of  functional  psychology  must  be  considered 
as  a  type  of  overt  action  performed  for  the  purpose  of 
control."  4  Hence,  "even  as  the  first  locomotive,  impractical 

1  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  89. 

2  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  pp.  72f. 

3  The  Differentiation  of  the  Religious  Consciousness,  pp.  38f. 

4  A  Study  in  the  Psychology  of  Ritualism,  p.  8.    In  the  same  paragraph 
Henke  refers  to  the  ceremonial  as  "designed  for  control."    This  state 
ment,   however,    is   so   obviously   incompatible   with   the   psychological 
standpoint  of  the  essay  that  it  must  be  regarded  as  an  inadvertence,  un 
less  the  expression  is  intended  as  the  equivalent  of  "performed  for  the 
purpose  of  control." 

As  of  the  origin,  so  of  the  perpetuity  of  ritual.  "The  ritual  that  has 
lost  its  vitality  cannot  survive"  (p.  82).  What  preserves  the  statement 
from  tautology  is  the  preceding  sentence,  "Practicality  is,  withal,  the 
keyword  to  the  situation."  "The  survival  of  ritualism,"  we  are  told,  "is 
dependent  upon  keeping  intact  a  type  of  social  consciousness  that  finds 
the  ritualistic  reaction  a  valuable  method  of  control"  (p.  81).  "Wherever 
a  comparatively  primitive  type  of  ritual  survives  in  higher  stages  of 
culture,  the  social  consciousness  back  of  it  still  finds  it  a  practical  method 
of  control"  (p.  10).  "Ceremonial  performances  that  have  lost  their  prac 
tical  significance,  though  they  may  continue  for  awhile  through  sheer 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  335 

as  it  may  be  to-day,  grew  out  of  practical  demands,  so  the 
ritual  has  been  an  instrument  of  practical  control."  l 

Only  through  an  unusual  extension  of  the  term  may  we 
call  i religious'  all  those  practices  of  primitive  life  by  which 
a  control  is  effected  over  such  acts  as  are  thought  to  be  of 
greatest  social  import.  Instead  of  insisting  on  a  narrower 
delimitation  of  the  concept  'religious,'  however,  we  wish 
rather  to  dispute  the  thesis  that  either  rites  and  ceremonies 
or  primitive  religions  (whose  central  features,  in  the  view  of 
functionalists,  are  customs  and  ceremonies  of  various  sorts) 
are  definable  as  systems  or  agencies  of  practical  control,.  We 
call  attention  to  three  very  general  and  fundamental  facts. 

(l)  It  is,  indeed,  unquestionable  both  that  some  cere 
monies  are  essentially  agencies  of  practical  control  and  also 
that  very  many  others  exhibit  the  influence  of  the  motive  of 
control.  The  amazing  diversity  and  complexity  of  primitive 
ceremonies,  however,  makes  it  difficult  to  believe  that  they 
all  are  utilitarian  either  in  origin  or  in  purpose.  Nor  is  au 
thority  lacking  behind  which  such  a  doubt  may  shield  itself. 
Durkheim,  for  example,  whose  interpretation  of  Australian 
totemism  is  one  of  the  most  thorough  as  well  as  the  most 
recent  that  we  possess,  maintains  that  "we  have  here  a 
whole  group  of  ceremonies  whose  sole  purpose  is  to  awaken 
certain  ideas  and  sentiments,  to  attach  the  present  to  the 
past  or  the  individual  to  the  group.  Not  only  are  they 
unable  to  serve  useful  ends,  but  the  worshippers  themselves 
demand  none."  2  One  who  lays  aside  for  the  time  being  all 

force  of  habit,  soon  lose  their  vitality  and  fall  away"  (p.  81).  Inciden 
tally  it  may  be  remarked  that  inertia  is  not  as  negligible  a  factor  as  func 
tionalists  are  inclined  to  assume.  What  we  shall  contend  with  reference 
to  the  origin  of  ceremonial,  moreover,  holds  true  also  of  its  survival:  a 
variety  of  non-practical  considerations  must  be  recognized.  As  Stratton 
says  in  his  analysis  of  the  various  "inner  supports"  of  ceremonial:  "But 
religion  does  not  forever  keep  its  eye  on  tangible  benefits  to  be  obtained; 
the  ritual  is  expressive,  and  has  in  it  no  more  of  mere  prudence  and  calcula 
tion  than  has  the  gold  upon  a  state-house  dome,  or  the  bannered  proces 
sion  of  a  party  victorious  at  the  polls."  The  Psychology  of  the  Religious 
Life,  p.  145. 

1  Henke,  op.  cit.,  p.  10. 

2  The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life,  tr.  by  J.  W.  Swain,  p.  378. 


336  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

allegiance  or  deference  to  a  particular  psychological  school, 
will  be  able  to  catalog  a  considerable  number  of  other  than 
strictly  practical  motives  that  operate  in  the  genesis  and 
development  of  ceremonial.  Such  motives  are:  (a)  The 
pleasure  derived  in  various  ways,  as,  for  example,  from  the 
mere  actions,  motions,  and  gesticulations,1  from  the  element 
of  rhythm  in  movement  and  speech,  or  from  the  heightening 
of  emotions;  2  (b)  the  play  impulse,  as  expressed  either  in 
physical  movements  or  in  the  creations  of  the  imagination;  3 
(c)  the  mere  repetition,  through  suggestion  and  imitation, 
of  various  sorts  of  accidental  and  spontaneous  actions,  and 
of  such  as  result  from  inhibitions,  super-excitations,  or  dis 
charges  of  energy  generally;  (d)  the  consciousness  of  doing 
things  as  they  have  been  done,  of  continuing  the  ways  of 
earlier  generations  and  thus  of  maintaining  continuity, — 
hence  a  certain  regard  for  the  permanent,  together  with  a 
sense  of  safety  and  the  feeling  of  relationship  to  a  larger 
company;  (e)  the  passion  for  embellishment;  (f)  desire  for 
self-expression,  as  well  as  publicly  to  acknowledge  that  cer 
tain  beliefs  or  relations  are  cherished;  (g)  sense  of  fitness, 
that  which  is  peculiarly  important  or  honored  demanding 
formality  or  pomp;  (h)  the  impulse  to  imitate  and  to  render 
vivid  through  action  deeds  and  events  in  the  lives  of  the 
gods;  4  (i)  the  commemoration  and  recollection  of  the  past, 
"in  a  way  making  it  present  by  a  means  of  a  veritable 
dramatic  representation;"  5  (j)  the  renewal  by  the  group  of 
"the  sentiment  which  it  has  of  itself  and  of  its  unity;"6 

1  The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life,  tr.  by  J.  W.  Swain,  p.  381. 

2  Cf.  Wundt,  Elements  of  Folk  Psychology,  tr.  by  E.  L.  Schaub,  p.  95. 

3  Cf.  Seashore,  "The  Play  Impulse  and  Attitude  in  Religion,"  American 
Journal  of  Theology,  Vol.  XIV,   1910,  pp.  505-520,  and  Psychology  in 
Daily  Life,  pp.  22ff.;  Durkheim,   The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious 
Life,  pp.  379ff.;  for  the  inclusion  in  ceremonial  of  humorous  episodes,  cf. 
Wundt,  op.  cit.,  p.  464. 

4  For  an  admirable  discussion  of  this  and  the  three  preceding  motives, 
see  the  chapters  on  ritualism  and  public  worship  in  Stanton  Coit's  Na 
tional  Idealism  and  a  State  Church  and  The  Soul  of  America;  see  also  Strat- 
ton,  The  Psychology  of  the  Religious  Life,  pp.  I4iff. 

5  Durkheim,  The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life,  p.  372. 

6  Ibid.,  p.  375. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  337 

"rites  are  means  by  which  the  social  group  reaffirms  itself 
periodically."  1  Of  these  various  motives,  functionalism,  in 
its  concern  to  discover  the  practical  in  religion,  is  for  the 
most  part  oblivious.  King,  whose  attitude  is  considerably 
more  plastic  than  that  of  the  other  writers  of  the  group  to 
which  he  belongs,  does  indeed  recognize  the  importance  for 
ceremonial  not  merely  of  "unconscious  changes  .  .  .  trans 
mitted  by  imitation  and  social  heredity"  2  but  also  of  the 
play  impulse.3  But  even  this  slight  departure  from  the  con 
cepts  of  adjustment  and  practical  control  is  regarded  du 
biously  by  a  fellow-functionalist.  Commenting  on  it,  Henke 
remarks  that  "the  place  of  play  appears  of  minimum  im 
portance  in  the  origin  of  ritualism.  Practical  interests  are 
by  far  the  most  important.  Play  itself,  when  viewed  from 
the  agent's  standpoint,  is  largely  a  practical  interest.  .  .  . 
In  the  development  and  survival  of  the  ceremony,  so-called 
play  activities  may  emerge,  but  not  without  practical 
implications."  4 

(2)  When  we  turn  from  ceremonial  to  the  question  of  the 
objects  regarded  in  early  religion  as  sacred,  we  find  functional 
interpretations  somewhat  less  guilty  of  purchasing  con 
sistency  at  the  cost  of  a  full  recognition  of  the  various  psy 
chological  factors  involved.  Says  Ames,  with  reference  to 
the  development  of  Hebrew  religion:  "The  first  and  lowest 
stage  ...  is  that  in  which  anything  which  catches  attention 
and  excites  wonder  is  considered  sacred.  The  Semitic  folk 
lore  and  custom  show  the  evidence  of  such  a  stage  when 
rivers,  springs,  trees,  stones,  caves,  and  animals,  particularly 
such  objects  as  were  unusual  in  appearance  or  in  value,  were 
sacred."  5  Henke  likewise  emphasizes  the  role  played  by 
"the  moving  object"  as  well  as  by  "anything  unusual  in 
shape,  size,  position,  or  color."  6  Similarly,  King  acknowl- 

1  Durkheim,  The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life,  p.  387. 

2  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  48. 

3  Ibid.,  pp.  s8f. 

4  A  Study  in  the  Psychology  of  Ritualism,  pp.  34f. 
6  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  p.  172. 

6  A  Study  in  the  Psychology  of  Ritualism,  pp.  48f. 


338  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

edges  that  various  animals  and  forms  of  vegetation,  as  well 
even  as  inanimate  objects  "may  easily  and  in  quite  explain 
able  ways  arouse  a  sort  of  spontaneous  attention  in  people."  1 
"There  can  be  no  doubt,"  he  writes  concerning  the  Niger 
tribes,  "that  it  is  some  physical  peculiarity  of  tree,  shrub, 
or  animal,  a  peculiarity  of  some  practical  significance,  pos 
sibly,  which  has  thrust  it  upon  their  attention  and  thus  made 
it  an  appropriate  dwelling  for  the  ancestral  spirit."  2  The 
very  presence  in  this  last  quotation  of  the  parenthetical 
phrase,  "a  peculiarity  of  some  practical  significance,  pos 
sibly,"  of  itself  tells  a  story.  Why  should  the  phrase  have 
occurred  to  the  writer  at  all?  And  might  not  an  objector  to 
functional  interpretation  with  equal  truth  have  written  "a 
peculiarity  of  no  practical  significance,  possibly?"  King's 
parenthetical  phrase  but  prepares  for  a  later  assertion  of  a 
stronger  nature:  "So  also  with  physical  objects  of  unusual 
size  or  shape,  or  such  as  possess  dangerous  qualities.  In  all 
cases  it  should  be  borne  in  mind  that  the  occasion  which 
excites  attention,  i.  e.,  the  strange  and  unusual  object  or 
phenomenon,  is  first  recognized  because  it  seems  to  have  a 
close  connection  with  some  of  the  already  existing  activities 
of  the  individual  or  the  group.  ...  It  is  often  said  that 
for  the  savage  the  idea  of  the  supernatural  has  its  rise  in 
that  which  appears  to  him  in  some  way  unusual.  .  .  .  This 
is  all  true,  but  it  is  important  to  remember  that  these  things 
attract  the  savage  because  of  the  part  they  appear  to  play 
in  something  he  is  occupied  in  doing."  3  Thus,  whereas  func 
tional  writers  generally  admit  into  their  accounts  of  the 
sacred  and  the  supernatural,  factors  emphasized  more  es 
pecially  by  Max  Mtiller,  Marett,  and  Clodd,  King  (and, 
though  perhaps  less  clearly,  Ames  and  Henke  also)  recognize 
that  this  might  be  a  cause  for  challenging  their  orthodoxy. 
Hence  the  but  partially  true,  if  not  wholly  unwarranted, 
thesis  that,  after  all,  to  receive  recognition  and  to  impress 
themselves  forcibly  upon  the  mind,  objects  must  be  con- 

1  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  231. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  232,  note. 

3  Ibid.,  p.  315. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  339 

nected  with  the  various  activities  or  practical  interests  that 
represent  the  life  of  the  individual  and  of  the  group. 

(3)  It  is  becoming  increasingly  clear  that,  second  in  impor 
tance  to  no  other  element  in  primitive  thought,  is  the  belief 
that  there  is  operative  in  nature  generally,  as  well  as  in  hu 
man  affairs  and  in  the  capacities  particularly  of  exceptional 
individuals,  a  mysterious,  impersonal,  quasi-mechanical 
power,  variously  called  manitou,  wakonda,  orenda,  mana, 
pokunt,  yek,  nauala,  etc.1  That  this  concept  has  "probably 
played  a  large  part  in  the  unfolding  of  human  thought,  and 
has  consequently  reacted  in  important  ways  upon  behavior 
and  custom,"  l  King  himself  is  forced  to  recognize.  If, 
however,  "the  mysterious  power"  has  been  an  important 
factor  in  the  genesis  and  development  of  customs,  cere 
monials,  and  religion  generally,  the  inadequacy  of  the  func 
tional  standpoint  is  clear.  In  fact,  speaking  of  this  concept, 
King  himself  makes  the  following  frank  admission:  "It  is 
difficult  to  relate  it  exactly  to  what  has  thus  far  been  said  of 
the  development  of  the  value-consciousness,  and  yet  it  has 
had  a  part  in  that  development  which  we  trust  will  not  seem 
to  be  altogether  adventitious,  even  though  we  should  stand 
firmly  upon  the  theory  as  thus  far  outlined."  3 

The  three  broadly  important  considerations  which  we  have 
thus  indicated  render  unsuccessful  functionalism's  restriction 
of  the  motives  and  the  factors  even  of  early  religion  to  such 
as  are  of  practical  import  or  as  relate  to  control.  Numerous 
are  the  characteristics  which  enable  objects  to  arouse  atten 
tion  and  interest;  very  rich  and  diverse  are  the  activities  and 
the  emotions,  the  longings  and  demands,  of  individual 

1  Cf.  more  particularly  the  discussions  and  the  bibliographical  refer 
ences  of  Lovejoy,  "The  Fundamental  Concept  of  the  Primitive  Philoso 
phy,"  Monist,  Vol.  XVI,  1906,  pp.  357-382;  King,  The  Development  of 
Religion,  pp.  132-164;  Leuba,  A  Psychological  Study  of  Religion,  pp.  70-84, 
I22f.,  163;  Goldenweiser,  "Spirit,  Mana,  and  the  Religious  Thrill,"  Jour 
nal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific  Methods,  Vol.  XII,   1915, 
pp.  632-640;  Durkheim,    The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life, 
pp.  62,  188-239. 

2  King,  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  132. 

3  Ibid. 


340  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

minds  and  of  groups.  As  Mr.  Eastman  states  in  a  paper 
which  appears  as  these  words  are  being  written,  "life  has  an 
interest  in  living,"  "  organisms  seriously  thirst  after  experi 
ence  in  general";  1  and,  as  we  shall  imply  in  what  is  now  to 
follow,  individuals  seek  for  meanings  no  less  than  for  ways  of 
adjustment  and  they  strive  for  greater  fullness  of  personal 
and  of  social  life. 

II 

The  attitude  of  the  functionalist  in  its  polemic  phase  is 
vigorously  expressed  by  King  when  he  affirms  that  "the  old 
method  of  trying  to  determine  the  essential  qualities  of  the 
religious  consciousness  ...  by  an  analysis  of  religion  in 
and  of  itself  is  scarcely  more  profitable  than  the  scholastic 
explication  of  concepts."  2  So  severe  an  indictment  as  this 
of  the  value  of  structural  analysis  cannot  be  expected  to 
receive  universal  assent.  Even  the  dissenters,  however, 
would  gladly  join  in  the  functionalist's  insistence  that  it  is 
both  unscientific  and  futile  to  account  for  religious  phe 
nomena  in  terms  of  some  postulated  religious  capacity, 
whether  this  be  described  as  a  special  faculty,  as  an  instinct, 
or  as  a  perception  of  the  infinite.  Religion  is  not  as  inde 
pendent  an  element  of  experience  as  these  latter  interpreta 
tions  imply.  It  is  involved,  body  and  soul,  in  the  fortunes 
and  transformations  of  experience  as  a  whole.  This  being 
the  case,  religion  cannot  be  significantly  interpreted  except 
by  such  methods  as  are  capable  of  disclosing  the  meanings 
of  experience  generally  as  these  come  to  light  either  through 
logical  analysis  or,  more  particularly,  in  and  through  the 
process  of  development  by  which  individuals  become  con 
scious  of  their  own  nature  and  of  the  world  in  which  they 
live.  In  any  account  of  origin  and  growth,  however,  it  is 
but  an  expenditure  of  breath  to  explain  in  terms  of  hy- 
pothetically  given  capacities  to  do  or  to  bring  forth  given 
results.  To  a  certain  extent,  therefore,  we  must  sympathize 

1  "The  Will  to  Live,"  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Scientific 
Methods,  Vol.  XIV,  1917,  pp.  104,  107. 

2  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  22. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  341 

with  the  initial  attitude  of  the  functionalist.  But  may  one 
say,  as  King  does,  that  "the  scientist  cannot  be  satisfied  to 
regard  anything  as  innate.  His  so-called  ultimate  data  are 
ultimate  only  for  the  philosopher  or  for  the  non-scientific 
mind."  1  Is  not  the  very  opposite  true?  In  so  far  as  one 
wishes  to  distinguish  between  philosopher  and  scientist,  or 
between  the  philosophy  and  the  psychology  of  religion,  must 
it  not  be  said  that  some  of  philosophy's  most  important 
problems  relate  to  assumptions  which  the  scientist  accepts 
without  further  ado  and  which  are  in  this  sense  ultimate 
data  for  him? 

The  significant  fact  is  that  the  functional  interpretation 
of  religion,  even  in  the  skillful  hands  of  King,  does  start  at 
a  beginning  which  is  assumed  without  any  effort  toward 
examination.  The  world  of  mere  objective  fact  and  of  ex 
istences  independent  of  interests  and  strivings,  indeed,  is 
held  to  emerge,  through  processes  of  abstraction  and  idea- 
tional  construction,  from  an  experience  which  is  funda 
mentally  appreciative  or  valuational.  This  latter  experience, 
furthermore,  though  described  as  "a  relatively  primary  form 
of  conscious  process,"  2  is  brought  into  connection  with 
"man's  active  relation  to  his  environment,  both  physical  and 
social."  3  Man's  active  relation,  however,  is  an  expression 
of  his  instinctive  and  impulsive  equipment,  and  this  it  is 
which  (although,  as  we  shall  presently  see,  not  always  clearly 
or  consistently)  represents  King's  ultimate  datum.  We 
shall  not  stress  the  point  that  there  are  here  simply  assumed, 
as  matters  of  fact,  those  particular  objective  existences 
(namely,  organisms  or,  to  use  King's  term,  'men,'  charac 
terized  by  impulsive  tendencies  of  various  sorts  and  therefore 
by  active  relations  with  other  particular  objects,  physical 
and  social)  which  are  represented  in  the  analysis  of  experi 
ence  as  intellectual  abstractions  justified  only  by  reference  to 
interests  that  are  fundamentally  appreciative  or  valuational. 
Our  immediate  concern  is  rather  to  point  out  that  functional 
interpretations  of  religion,  although  aspiring  to  be  genetic, 
nevertheless  do  assume  certain  data  as  given,  do  actually 

1  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  26.  2  Ibid.,  p.  44.  3  Ibid. 


342  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

assume  certain  qualities  as  innate  in  a  very  important  sense 
of  that  term. 

It  is  in  the  writings  of  Ames  and  Henke  that  we  find  the 
most  definite  statements  both  as  to  what  specific  interests 
or  instincts  are,  for  functionalism,  fundamental  in  early  re 
ligion,  and  as  to  the  precise  character  of  these  interests  and 
instincts.  Says  Ames,  "Food  and  sex  are  the  great  interests 
of  the  individual  and  of  society.  These  may  work  out  in 
various  secondary  forms,  but  the  'ground  patterns'  of  man's 
life  are  determined  by  these  two  elemental  forces."  l  With 
great  care,  therefore,  Ames  traces  the  ramifying  influences  of 
food  and  sex  upon  social  and  economic  organization,  custom 
and  taboo,  ceremonials  and  magic,  sacrifice,  and  other  ele 
ments  that  have  either  entered  into  or  have  conditioned  the 
development  of  the  various  religions.  As  regards  the  exact 
nature  of  the  interests  of  food  and  sex  which  are  said  to  func 
tion  in  connection  with  religion,  Ames  does  not  leave  us  in 
doubt.  They  are  "  basal  instincts  "  and  are  "  so  characteristic 
of  the  whole  range  of  sentient  life  preceding  man  and  now 
existing  below  him  in  the  biological  scale  that  it  involves 
no  daring  assumption  to  infer  that  he  possessed  them  from 
the  most  rudimentary  stage  of  his  existence."  2  Henke 
agrees  with  Ames  in  emphasizing  the  interests  of  food  and 
sex.  He  feels  the  necessity,  however,  of  adding  at  least  two 
other  instincts,  fear  and  anger,  though  admitting  that  these 
are  "derivative,"  inasmuch  as  they  appear  as  "distinct 
emotional  reactions,"  when,  respectively,  "the  animal  had 
experienced  actual  danger  and  pain  in  quest  of  food,"  3 
and  when  "the  animal  was  frustrated  in  its  quest  for  food."  4 
Here  again  the  fundamental  factors  of  religion  are  conceived 
as  identical  with  instincts  as  they  manifest  themselves  on 
the  prehuman  level  of  existence.  "Primitive  man's  cere 
monies,"  it  is  contended,  "represent  the  functioning  of  in 
herited  tendencies  to  action.  .  .  .  Primitive  man  has  the 
sex  impulse,  and  consequently  the  marriage  ceremony."  5 

1  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  p.  33.  z  Ibid.,  p.  34. 

3  A  Study  in  the  Psychology  of  Ritualism,  p.  26.  4  Ibid.,  p.  31. 

5  Ibid.,  p.  36. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  343 

We  read,  indeed,  that  "to  the  writer  many  of  the  ceremonies 
described  by  the  anthropologist  seem  to  give  evidence  of 
thought  as  well  as  of  instinct  and  impulse,"  and  yet  it  is 
assumed  that  ceremony  may  be  "an  expression  of  innate 
hereditary  acts  and  nothing  more."  1 

The  attitude  of  King  with  reference  to  the  points  just 
discussed  is  somewhat  elusive.  At  times  he  would  appear 
to  be  more  persistent  even  than  either  Ames  or  Henke  in 
his  search  for  origins.  More  positively,  certainly,  and  with 
greater  emphasis,  does  he  insist  on  the  necessity  of  exhibiting 
the  genesis  of  the  values  which  attach,  in  the  consciousness 
of  the  individual  and  of  the  group,  to  certain  objects  and 
practices.  With  less  hesitation  than  is  sometimes  displayed 
by  those  who  restrict  mental  life  to  a  means  of  adjustment, 
he  admits  that  "in  a  very  general  sense  .  .  .  everything 
which  attracts  attention  may  be  the  subject  of  a  value- 
judgment."  2  Nevertheless,  in  allegiance  to  the  principle 
with  which  he  operates,  King  contends  that  it  is  only  when 
response  is  delayed  and  a  series  of  mediating  acts  conditions 
the  desired  satisfaction  that  objects  or  situations  acquire 
any  considerable  value  for  consciousness.  King's  account 
of  the  ways  in  which  intermediate  processes  originate  and 
thus  generate  such  valuations  as  precondition  religious  at 
titudes  represents  a  highly  suggestive  bit  of  analysis. 
Nevertheless,  a  close  study  of  the  argument  leaves  one  in 
some  uncertainty  as  to  whether  or  not  there  is  agreement 
with  the  view  of  Ames  and  Henke,  that  the  basal  impulses  of 
religion  are  to  be  found,  not  in  the  experience  of  conscious 
individuals  as  members  of  a  social  order,  but  in  something 
far  more  primitive,  namely,  in  the  demands  of  organisms 
upon  their  environment.  On  the  one  hand,  King's  analysis, 
as  has  already  been  indicated,  seems  to  terminate  in  impul 
sive  and  instinctive  activities  and  there  are  suggestions  every 
now  and  again  of  a  biological  point  of  view.  On  the  other 
hand,  we  read  the  positive  statement,  "In  no  intelligible 
way  can  the  religious  consciousness  or  religious  acts  be 

1  A  Study  in  the  Psychology  of  Ritualism,  p.  36. 

2  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  46. 


344  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

thought  of  as  directly  related  to  the  biological  struggle  for 
existence."  l  It  may  not  be  altogether  without  significance 
that  King  speaks  preferably  in  terms,  not  of  organism,  but 
of  life-process.2  The  latter  term  possesses  a  certain  flexi 
bility  and  indefiniteness  and  one  cannot  avoid  the  impression 
that  it  is  these  qualities  which  have  commended  it.  It  seems, 
somehow,  to  stand  now  for  biological  processes  but  again 
for  the  general  movement  of  a  dynamic  experience.  In  any 
event,  the  life-process  is  not  represented  as  merely  practical 
in  its  concerns;  to  it  are  ascribed  all  sorts  of  spontaneous 
manifestations,  play  interests,  and  other  non-utilitarian 
activities.3  King's  account  does  not  avoid  a  similar  vague 
ness  as  regards  the  manner  in  which  conscious  values  are 
thought  to  emerge  through  complications  and  delays  of  re 
sponse.  The  initial  explanation  is  based  on  the  failure  of 
individuals  to  secure  an  immediate  satisfaction  of  needs  and 
desires.  Nevertheless,  as  King  assures  us  in  a  footnote,  "we 
do  not  ignore  the  social  factor  in  the  valuational  conscious 
ness.  It  is  of  the  greatest  importance,  but  we  shall  reserve 
it  for  treatment  in  another  connection."  4  What  we  find  in 
these  other  connections,  however,  is  the  statement  either 
that  the  group  creates  certain  values  or  that  it  enhances 
and  renders  permanent  "the  simple  values  brought  to  con 
sciousness  by  the  growth  of  intermediate  activities,"  causing 
the  latter  to  appear  "genuinely  ultimate  and  universal."  5 
Even  such  statements  as  these  scarcely  dispel  one's  doubt 
as  to  King's  precise  position.  Are  the  valuations  involved 
in  all  religions  intelligible  except  by  reference  to  conscious 
individuals  living  among  and  affected  by  others  of  their  kind, 
and  seeking,  more  or  less  clearly  and  more  or  less  deviously, 
wider  and  deeper  social  relationships?  King  seems  to  shy 
at  a  view  as  biological  as  that  of  Ames  and  Henke  and  yet 
his  functional  predilections  prevent  a  negative  answer  to 
the  question. 

1  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  26. 

2  C/.,  for  example,  ibid.,  pp.  18,  22,  23,  26,  37,  59,  61,  62,  etc. 

3  Cf.,  for  example,  ibid.,  pp.  83,  100,  103,  in. 

4  Ibid.,  p.  45,  note.  6  Ibid.,  p.  68. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  345 

Similar  differences  of  emphasis  occur  in  connection  with 
the  accounts  which  the  various  functional  writers  give  of 
the  development  of  religion.  For  example,  the  more  unam 
biguous  stress  which  Ames  and  Henke  place  upon  certain 
instincts  and  interests  of  the  organism  causes  them  to  sug 
gest,  at  times,  that  the  development  may  be  read  in  terms 
of  an  increasing  refinement  and  specialization  of  desire.1  In 
the  main,  however,  functionalists  agree  that,  inasmuch  as 
religion  arises  in  connection  with  those  interests  which  in 
dividuals  within  a  group  share  and  pursue  in  common,  the 
development  of  religion  corresponds  with  the  changing  char 
acter  of  that  which  is  of  most  vital  significance  to  the  group 
as  a  whole.  The  appearance  of  higher  types  of  religion, 
therefore,  is  an  expression  of  widened  and  elaborated  social 
interests.  King  even  goes  so  far  as  to  say  that  "the  deistic 
conceptions  of  different  times  and  races  are,  in  the  main, 
quite  discrete  and  unrelated  to  each  other  except  in  the  fact 
that  they  are  all  varying  modes  of  social  reaction  and  social 
determination."  2  For  the  functionalist,  of  course,  changes 
in  social  interests  are  explicable  in  terms  of  changed  adjust 
ments  which  have  become  necessary  on  the  part  of  the  or 
ganism  or  the  life-process.  Throughout  their  writings,  there 
fore,  much  stress  is  laid  upon  such  factors  as  "the  failure 
of  the  food  supply  through  natural  causes  or  through  the 
encroachment  of  other  tribes,  the  discovery  of  new  lands 
or  resources,  the  invention  of  tools  or  weapons,"  3  as  well  as 
upon  tribal  struggles,  warfare,  and  migration. 

Admitting  that  the  phenomena  of  religion  cannot  be 
understood  without  employing  a  developmental  point  of 
view  and  acknowledging  the  suggestiveness  with  which 
functional  writers  have  performed  their  task,  one  may  never 
theless  inquire  whether  all  of  the  demands  of  genetic  inter- 

1  C/.,   for    example,   Ames,    The   Psychology   of  Religious   Experience, 
p.  117:  "To  a  far  later  day  than  is  usually  recognized  the  governing  im 
pulse  in  these  [the  sacrificial]  rites,  is  the  desire  for  food,  though  this 
may  become  refined  into  the  desire  for  a  particular  kind  of  food  more 
potent  or  spiritual  than  others." 

2  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  226. 

3  Ames,  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  p.  170. 


346  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

pretation  have  been  complied  with.  To  such  an  inquiry  we 
believe  that  a  negative  answer  must  be  given.  Our  reasons 
are  the  following: 

(i)  Functional  accounts  violate  those  principles  of  genetic 
logic  which  Baldwin  has  termed  "Canon  of  Progression," 
" Canon  of  Modal  Relevancy,"  and  "Canon  of  Modal 
Unity."  1  To  illustrate:  They  identify  the  food-interest 
as  it  functions  in  the  rise  and  development  of  religious  ex 
perience  with  the  food-impulse  of  the  "whole  range  of  sen 
tient  life."  To  do  this,  however,  or  even  to  describe  the 
former  as  a  'refinement'  of  the  latter,  is  highly  misleading. 
Human  individuals  not  merely  have  certain  feelings  and 
impulses,  but  they  are  conscious  of  these  and  of  themselves 
as  experiencing  them.  Indeed,  as  Green  and  many  others 
have  repeatedly  urged,  man  may  so  detach  himself  from 
any  desire  as  to  conceive  himself  "in  possible  enjoyment  of 
the  satisfaction  of  other  desires  .  .  .  and  the  desire  itself  is 
more  or  less  stimulated  or  checked,  according  as  its  gratifi 
cation  in  this  involuntary  forecast  appears  conducive  to 
happiness  or  otherwise."  2  Thus,  as  organic  impulses  and 
instincts  become  elements  in  the  self-conscious  life  of  in 
dividuals,  vast  changes  are  wrought.  On  the  one  hand,  the 
impulses  and  instincts  themselves  become  transformed;  on 
the  other,  new  desires  and,  with  them,  new  values  arise 
through  the  comparison,  stimulation,  and  repression  of  its 
acts  by  the  self,  and  through  the  aspiration  of  the  self  to 
acquire  a  nature  which  as  yet  reveals  itself  only  to  the  con 
structive  imagination.  A  genetic  account  which  fails, 
through  its  point  of  view,  even  to  recognize  the  changes  just 
indicated  or  to  present  an  analysis  of  the  food-impulse  and 
other  interests  as  these  come  to  manifest  themselves  in  the 
actual  experience  of  human  individuals,  cannot  be  regarded 
as  satisfactory.3  Functionalism,  as  represented  at  any  rate 


1  Thought  and  Things,  or  Genetic  Logic,  Vol.  I,  p.  23. 

2  Prolegomena  to  Ethics,  §  127. 


3  For  an  interesting  account  of  the  new  forms  and  the  changed  signifi 
cance  assumed  by  the  food-impulse  in  human  life,  see  Wundt,  Ethics, 
Vol.  I,  tr.  by  Gulliver  and  Titchener,  pp.  169-177. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  347 

by  King,  has  indeed  undertaken  to  point  out  the  conditions 
under  which  impulsive  acts  come  to  acquire  a  value  for  con 
sciousness,  but  the  consciousness  of  the  value  has  for  the 
most  part  been  treated  as  epiphenomenal  rather  than  as 
itself  a  transforming  and  a  creative  factor  within  experience. 
There  is  a  general  failure  on  the  part  of  functional  writers, 
moreover,  to  do  full  justice  to  those  changes  in  impulsive  and 
instinctive  acts  which  result  from  the  fact  that  human  life 
is  essentially  social.  It  is  not  the  bare  performance  of  in 
stinctive  acts,  the  satisfaction  of  appetite,  or  the  adjustment 
to  the  environing  conditions  of  nature,  that  is  focal  in  con 
sciousness  even  in  the  case  of  primitive  man.  On  the  con 
trary,  the  concern  is  with  matters  of  recognized  social  in 
terest.  Custom,  taboo,  ceremonial,  expressions  of  approval 
and  disapproval,  of  encouragement  and  of  command,  sur 
charge  even  the  simplest  acts  with  values  and  emotions  not 
attached  to  them  in  prehuman  stages  of  conduct.  The  mean 
ing  which  acts  and  objects  possess  for  the  human  individual, 
therefore,  cannot  be  arrived  at  by  any  method  that  considers 
merely  the  function  which  the  acts  subserve  and  the  role 
which  the  objects  play  in  the  life-process.  Consider,  by  way 
of  illustration,  the  phenomenon  of  sacrifice.  Ames  believes 
that  he  can  safeguard  his  interpretation  by  studying  the 
results  which  the  acts  involved  effect.  This  leads  to  the 
conclusion  that  the  "central  feature"  in  the  rite,  "the  most 
basic  and  characteristic  act,"  and  "the  governing  impulse," 
all  relate  to  the  food-process.1  How  remote  all  this  is  from 
expressing  "the  meaning  attached  to  these  [sacrificial]  acts," 
should  be  clear  to  anyone  who  has  not  set  out  to  study  them 
with  definite  psychological  prepossessions. 

(2)  Closely  related  to  the  foregoing  is  a  second  failure  of 
functionalism  as  a  genetic  account.  The  commendable  en 
deavor  to  avoid  the  errors  of  those  who  would  find  through 
out  all  the  various  stages  of  development  the  characteristic 
traits  of  advanced  religions,3  leads  too  frequently  to  the 

1  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  pp.  n6f. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  116. 

3  That  is,  in  the  language  of  Baldwin,  the  "fallacy  of  Implication,  or 


348  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

converse  fallacy  of  interpreting  the  higher  religions  in  terms 
of  the  lower.1  Geneticism  demands  that  each  stage  be  dealt 
with  according  to  principles  determined  by  its  own  nature. 
Even  granting  that,  in  the  case  of  primitive  religions,  one 
cannot  avoid  depending  very  largely  upon  the  point  of  view 
of  adjustment,  of  acts  involved  and  results  effected,  such 
external  or  objective  considerations  fail  hopelessly  to  ex 
hibit  the  meaning  of  the  higher  forms  of  religious  experience. 
What  has  just  been  said  with  reference  to  sacrifice  affords  a 
clue  as  to  the  reason  for  a  complaint  recently  made  to  the 
writer  by  a  thoughtful  student.  He  expressed  disappoint 
ment  over  the  fact,  that,  while  functional  accounts  intro 
duced  for  him  a  greater  measure  of  order  and  meaning  into 
the  highly  diverse  and  chaotic  religious  phenomena  of 
primitive  peoples,  they  continued  to  impress  him  as  utterly 
strange  and  artificial  with  reference  to  any  religious  experi 
ence  of  which  he  had  direct  knowledge. 

(3)  In  discussing  the  higher  manifestations  of  religion, 
functionalists  of  necessity  shift  on  occasion  from  the  point 
of  view  of  adjustment  or  adaptation  to  that  of  personal 
realization.    This  fluctuation  of  viewpoint,  however,  occurs 
without  any  conscious,  or  at  any  rate  any  explicitly  indicated, 
appreciation  of  the  difference  between  them.    Nor,  of  course, 
is  there  any  endeavor  to  trace  the  steps  by  which  a  transition 
occurs  from  the  stage  of  religion  characterized  in  terms  of 
adjustment  to  those  higher  stages  in  which  the  latter  is 
either  displaced  or  supplemented  by  the  motive  of  personal 
realization. 

(4)  Without  question  there  is  truth  in  the  functionalist's 
contention  that  "religious  types  are  not  related  to  one  an 
other  in  causal  or  sequential  terms,"  that  "  there  is  no  con 
tinuum  of  reason  or  perception,"   and  that  we  may  not 
"trace  a  gradual  unfolding  of  some  innate  concept  of  a  di 
vine  or  ethical  ruler  of  the  universe."  2    On  the  other  hand, 

the  Implicit,  or  the  Potential."  Thought  and  Things,  or  Genetic  Logic, 
Vol.  I,  p.  24. 

1  Baldwin's  "fallacy  of  Equality,"  ibid.,  p.  23. 

2  King,  The  Development  of  Religion,  pp.  214,  216,  and  226,  respectively. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  349 

there  is  an  underestimation  of  the  role  that  thought  does 
play  and  therefore  also  of  the  degree  of  continuity  actually 
present,  if  one  asserts  that  the  various  stages  of  religion  are 
"quite  discrete  and  unrelated  to  each  other  except  in  ... 
that  they  are  all  varying  modes  of  social  reaction  and  social 
determination."  1  The  development  of  religion  cannot, 
indeed,  be  regarded  as  the  evolution  of  an  idea  or  of  a 
thought.  Nevertheless,  thought  is  a  genuine,  and,  it  is  im 
portant  to  note,  a  constantly  increasing  factor  in  the  de 
velopment.  Moreover,  it  does  more  than  merely  secure 
particular  satisfactions  and  adjustments;  its  acts  and  its 
results  are  far  less  discrete  than  the  functionalist  holds, 
(a)  Thought  is  concerned  not  alone  with  the  situations  of 
practical  difficulty  that  arise  from  time  to  time  but  also  with 
questions  that  have  arisen  in  the  course  of  its  own  activity 
and  with  the  examination  and  elaboration  of  earlier  conclu 
sions.  Thus,  there  is  a  measure  of  continuity  within  the 
thought-life  of  peoples,  and  this  continuity  reflects  itself  to  a 
certain  extent  in  their  religion,  (b)  Thought  is  instrumental 
not  merely  in  effecting  adjustments  to  stimuli  but  in  modi 
fying  the  stimuli  through  changes  which  it  inaugurates  in 
the  environment.  To  this  extent  thought  becomes  objecti 
fied  and  a  certain  continuity  results,  (c)  Similarly,  thought 
not  merely  serves  the  demands  of  impulses  and  instincts  but 
it  judges  the  latter,  controls  and  reshapes  them;  it  introduces 
a  measure  of  harmony  and  unity,  and  it  evaluates  and  directs 
the  self  which  it  thus  creates  towards  goals  which  it  postu 
lates.  It  is  but  a  partial  truth  to  affirm  that  "the  knowing 
process,  wherever  it  is  alive  and  urgent,  is  concerned  with 
action,  with  the  adjustment  of  means  to  ends."  2  Thought 
is  operative  in  the  forming  of  ends  as  well  as  in  the  devising 
of  means.  Thus  again  does  thought  find  an  incarnation 
which  lends  a  certain  rational  continuity  to  life  and  to  re 
ligion,  (d)  Thought  effects  an  expansion  of  one's  world 
and,  proportionately,  alters  actions  and  reactions;  in  this  way 
again  it  is  operative  in  introducing  a  measure  of  rational 

1  King,  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  226.    Quoted  above,  p.  345. 
•  Ames,  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  p.  315. 


350  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

sequence  into  those  human  attitudes  and  evaluations  which 
for  the  functionalist  constitute  religion. 

(5)  Functionalism  is  inadequate  as  a  genetic  account  be 
cause  of  its  failure  thoroughly  and  consistently  to  recognize 
that  religion  is  not  merely  a  derivative  or  secondary  phe 
nomenon,1  but  is  itself  an  important  factor  in  social  evolu 
tion,  that  religion  is  not  merely  an  expression  of  those  values 
which  social  groups  have  in  various  ways  come  to  regard  as 
most  vital,  but  powerfully  determines  what  at  any  given 
time  are  regarded  as  the  most  vital  values.  The  indefinite- 
ness  of  functional  conceptions  of  religion  2  makes  them  ex 
tremely  elusive.  The  emphasis  of  the  discussions,  however, 
is  entirely  in  harmony  with  the  standpoint  from  which  re- 

1  Cf.  King,  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  214. 

2  Leuba  is  quite  justified  in  his  criticism  that  King  has  "singled  out 
a  means  of  connecting  together  the  whole  of  life,  and  not  one  that  can  be 
used  to  differentiate  any  particular  portion  of  it,"  and  in  his  contention 
that  Ames's  discussion  of  religion  in  its  relation  to  social  interests  and 
social  movements  involves  much  confusion  due  to  "juggling  with  the 
word."     Cf.  A  Psychological  Study  of  Religion,  pp.   50  and  54,  respec 
tively. 

Ames,  for  example,  sometimes  teaches  that  in  advanced  civilizations 
religion  exists  along  side  of  law,  art,  and  science,  not  merely  as  a  separate 
but  sometimes  even  as  an  antagonistic  interest  (The  Psychology  of  Relig 
ious  Experience,  p.  279),  that  the  religious  nature,  "though  not  some 
thing  distinguishable  and  separable  in  any  mechanical  and  exclusive 
way,"  possesses  just  as  much  "independence  and  uniqueness"  as  "one's 
artistic  nature  or  one's  scientific  nature"  (ibid.,  p.  290).  On  the  other 
hand,  however,  religion  is  defined  as  "just  the  consciousness  of  the  great 
interests  and  purposes  of  life  in  their  most  idealized  and  intensified  forms" 
(ibid.,  p.  280);  or,  somewhat  differently  still,  as  a  "phase  of  all  socialized 
human  experience"  (ibid.,  p.  280);  or  again,  as  "  a  participation  in  the 
ideal  values  of  the  social  consciousness"  (ibid.,  p.  356).  At  times,  more 
over,  religion  is  defined  in  terms  of  the  inclusiveness  of  its  ends  (ibid., 
p.  302);  at  other  times,  in  terms  of  the  felt  value  of  its  ends  (ibid.,  p.  168). 
To  give  one  more  example  of  a  confusing  ambiguity  in  the  concept  're 
ligious:'  we  are  told  that  "religion,  in  a  psychical,  as  well  as  a  scriptural 
sense,  is  a  matter  of  the  spirit  rather  than  of  the  letter"  (ibid.,  p.  368). 
In  spite  of  this  fact,  Ames  writes:  "In  primitive  groups  there  could  be  no 
non-religious  persons.  The  customs  were  imperative  and  inexorable. 
Anyone  who  would  not  conform  was  punished  or  expelled  from  the  group 
and  not  infrequently  was  put  to  death"  (ibid.,  p.  356). 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  351 

ligion  appears  as  a  product  of  various  psychological  and 
economic  causes  and  as  an  expression  or  reflection  or  phase 
of  the  most  idealized  interests,  of  social  experiences,  or  of 
the  ideal  values  of  the  social  consciousness.  If,  however,  as 
an  unbiased  scrutiny  inevitably  reveals,  religion  has  through 
out  been  one  of  the  most  important  factors  both  in  its  own 
further  development  and  in  the  modification  of  those  condi 
tions  that  have  reciprocally  influenced  it,  functionalism  must 
in  so  far  also  be  pronounced  unsatisfactory  as  a  genetic 
account  of  religion. 

Ill 

No  less  insistent  than  its  emphasis  upon  the  develop 
mental  approach  has  been  functionalism's  contention  of  the 
fundamentally  social  character  of  religion.  It  is  by  reference 
to  the  social  quality  that  the  religious  experience  is  differ 
entiated  from  the  valuational  attitude  generally,1  that  re 
ligion  is  distinguished  from  magic,2  that  religious  ceremonial 
is  set  apart  from  custom  as  such,3  that  religious  persons  are 
contrasted  with  the  non-religious.4  It  is  through  changes  in 
the  social  consciousness  that  modifications  and  developments 
of  ritual  are  accounted  for,5  and  that  the  growth  and  decay 
of  creeds  are  explained.6  Indeed,  the  persistent  claim  of  the 
essentially  social  character  of  all  that  falls  within  the  sphere 
of  religion,  coupled  with  statements  to  the  effect  that  "the 
man  who  enters  thoroughly  into  the  social  movements  of  his 
time  is  to  that  extent  genuinely  religious  though  he  may 
characterize  himself  otherwise,"  7  results  in  the  obliteration 
of  any  discernible  distinction  between  the  concepts  ( re 
ligious'  and  'social.'  Accordingly,  Ames  describes  non- 
religious  persons  as  "those  who  fail  to  enter  vitally  into  a 

1  Cf.  King,  The  Development  of  Religion,  pp.  63  ff. 

2  Cf.  ibid.,  pp.  iSyff.;  Ames,  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience, 

P-79- 

3  Cf.  Ames,  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  p.  72. 

4  Cf.  ibid.,  pp.  358ff. 

5  Cf.  Henke,  A  Study  in  the  Psychology  of  Ritualism,  pp.  57,  63. 

6  Ames,  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  pp.  3 Soft.,  396!!. 
'  Ibid.,  p.  358. 


352  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

world  of  social  activities  and  feelings."  1  But  is  not  theory 
here  riding  roughshod  over  classifications  well-nigh  univer 
sally  accepted?  Does  not  religion  itself,  as  Stratton  has  so 
suggestively  pointed  out,  involve  conflicting  motives,  in 
ducing,  it  is  true,  participation  in  social  action  and  feeling, 
but  also  the  very  contrary,  namely,  withdrawal  from,  if 
not  actual  repudiation  of,  all  obligations  to  the  interests  or 
welfare  of  fellow-men?  The  list  of  those  who  have  been 
acclaimed  'saints'  by  widely  different  religions  of  varying 
levels  of  development  contains  the  names  of  many  who,  by 
Ames's  definition,  would  be  excluded  entirely  from  the 
circle  of  the  religious!  But  we  would  not  dwell  on  this 
anomalous  situation  or  on  the  difficulty  which  Ames's  con 
ception  encounters  in  finding  a  place  for  those  religious 
prophets  and  geniuses  who  are  antagonistic  to  the  values 
and  attitudes  characteristic  of  their  groups  and  who  so  broke 
with  the  social  consciousness  as  to  fall  martyrs  to  it.  In 
stead  of  discussing  the  respects  in  which  the  religious  and 
the  social  are  too  closely  identified,  let  us  raise  the  question 
whether  functionalism  has  adequately  recognized  the  es 
sentially  social  phases  which  religion  does  possess.  In  at 
least  three  respects  do  there  seem  to  be  shortcomings. 

(i)  As  we  have  already  had  occasion  to  notice,  functional 
accounts  fail  to  take  notice  of  the  peculiarly  subtle  and  in 
tricate  ways  in  which  social  feelings  and  attitudes  are  en 
tangled  in  even  the  simplest  of  human  actions.  It  is  not 
sufficient  simply  to  point  to  the  influence  of  social  factors  in 
the  differentiation  of  the  religious  from  the  valuational  life 
generally.  Social  factors  enter  in  an  essential  way  into  the 
genesis  of  all  human  values.  They  affect  decisively  such 
matters  even  as  the  procuring  and  consumption  of  food,  sex 
relations,  and  the  attitude  of  hostility,  to  say  nothing  of  the 
selection  of  names,  the  phenomena  of  initiation,  the  con 
struction  of  huts  and  lodges,  clan  relationships,  etc.  It  de 
notes  an  inadequate  recognition  of  the  social  phase  of  re 
ligion  when  functionalism  represents  religious  acts  and  rites 
as  concerned  primarily,  if  not  exclusively,  with  such  external 
1  Ames,  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  p.  359. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  353 

ends,  for  example,  as  the  securing  of  food  or  the  multiplica 
tion  of  food  objects,  an  interpretation  that  must  seem  almost 
grotesque  to  the  one  engaged  in  such  acts  or  rites. 

(2)  The  functionalist  does  indeed  emphasize  the  fact  that 
it  is  only  those  acts  which  are  done  in  common  and  those 
values  which  are  shared  by  members  of  the  group  that  can 
acquire  the  intensity,  ideality,  and  permanence  requisite  to 
make  them  religious.  He  points  out  also  the  dependence  of 
certain  types  of  ceremonial  upon  specific  sorts  of  social 
structure.  Moreover,  he  admits  incidentally,  though,  as  we 
have  seen,  with  inadequate  appreciation,  that  the  per 
formance  of  religious  rites  does,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  con 
solidate  the  interests  and  vivify  the  spirit  of  the  group.  But 
more  than  all  this  needs  to  be  said  by  one  who  would  fully 
express  the  social  motive  in  religion.  For,  surely  in  its 
higher  stages  and  even,  as  we  are  coming  more  clearly  to  see, 
in  its  elementary  forms,  religious  acts  are  a  direct  evidence 
of  man's  longing  for  a  more  complete  and  social  selfhood  and 
of  his  endeavor  to  participate  more  fully  in  the  social  con 
sciousness.  In  exposing  the  fallacies  of  the  earlier  gift- 
theories  of  sacrifice,  Robertson  Smith  maintains  that  sacri 
ficial  rites  assumed  the  form  of  a  meal,  but  of  a  meal  which 
was  essentially  an  act  of  communion  in  which  the  deity  was 
believed  to  participate  along  with  the  worshippers.  Whether 
the  elimination  from  sacrifice  of  the  features  of  oblation  and 
renouncement  is  justified,  as  Wundt  maintains,1  or  leads  to 
a  distorted  interpretation,  as  Durkheim  holds,2  need  not 
here  concern  us.  The  important  consideration  is  the  ever 
increasing  evidence  that  sacrifice,  in  common  with  other  re 
ligious  acts,  expresses,  as  an  essential  motive,  a  desire  both 
for  a  certain  enlargement  such  as  comes  through  communion 
and  for  identification  with  a  more  inclusive  spirit  than  that 
of  the  human  individual.  Basing  the  assertion  on  the  earlier 
work  of  Spencer  and  Gillen,  Ames  maintains  that  the  In- 
tichiuma  ceremonies  of  the  Australian  tribes  "were  originally 
elaborate  efforts  to  increase  the  food  supply  by  increasing 

1  Elements  of  Folk  Psychology,  p.  434. 

2  The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life,  pp.  34off. 


354  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

the  totem."  l  The  evidence  which  Durkheim  has  assembled 
is  sufficient  to  indicate  that  such  a  view  should  not  stand 
unchallenged,  even  though  this  writer  may  be  passing  to 
an  equally  unsatisfactory  extreme  when  he  asserts  that  In- 
tichiuma  ceremonies  contain  as  two  essential  elements,  "an 
act  of  communion  and  an  act  of  oblation,"  2  and  that  even 
the  most  rudimentary  cults  known  to-day  exhibit  "the  most 
mystical  form  of  the  alimentary  communion."  3 

(3)  A  third  shortcoming  which  we  find  in  functionalism, 
so  far  as  its  recognition  of  the  social  is  concerned,  can  here 
but  receive  mention.  To  enter  into  a  discussion  as  to 
whether  such  a  standpoint  as  that  represented  by  Ames  and 
King  can  sufficiently  escape  subjectivism  to  provide  logically 
for  the  existence  of  any  reality  or  objects  independent  of  the 
experience  of  human  individuals,  or  even  of  a  single  in 
dividual,  would  be  to  repeat  numerous  arguments  and  coun 
ter  arguments  that  have  been  advanced  and  readvanced 
during  recent  years.  But  even  such  objective  existence  as 
King  gives  to  many  other  concepts  he  denies  to  those  of 
religion.  "Since  the  concepts  of  religion  symbolize  values 
rather  than  describe  an  objective  order  of  existence,"  he 
writes,  "the  psychologist  must  be  careful  to  avoid  treating 
them  in  the  same  way  as  he  would  the  concepts  of  science."  4 
What  the  religionist  regards  as  an  order  of  reality,  according 
to  King  and  functionalists  generally,  is  in  the  last  analysis 
a  manifestation  of  the  way  in  which  imagination  portrays 
the  fact  of  certain  valuational  experiences  enjoyed  by  the 
individual.  It  is  true,  of  course,  that,  in  addition  to  deities 
who  are  the  direct  embodiments  of  existing  valuational  at 
titudes  and  are  therefore  vital  to  experience,  there  are  oc 
casional  deities  who,  though  believed  to  exist,  are  not  wor 
shipped.  For  the  functionalist  such  deities  as  the  latter 
cannot  be  different  in  origin  from  those  about  whom  scrupu 
lously  observed  cults  center.  In  so  far,  therefore,  as  he  does 

1  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience,  p.  118. 

2  The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life,  p.  342. 

3  Ibid.,  p.  340. 

4  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  263. 


FUNCTIONAL  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  RELIGION  355 

not  find  them  to  be  purely  "play  deities"  constructed  upon 
the  analogy  of  those  who  are  actually  worshipped,  he  is 
compelled  to  regard  them  as  "  stranded  "  1  deities,  survivals 
of  a  period  whose  interests  radically  differed  from  those  of 
later  times.    He  is  unable  to  admit  that  the  lack  of  a  cult,  in 
the  case  of  certain  deities,  can  be  due  to  the  fact  that  these 
particular  deities  originated,  not  in  human  needs,  but  as  a  re 
sult  of  causal  inquiries  or  of  intellectual  processes.2     Nor 
could  he  concede  that  the  deity-concept  is  one  to  be  tested 
and  examined  by  methods  such  as  are  employed  to  determine 
whether  or  not  an  objective  fact  of  existence  is  being  de 
scribed.     Gods,  in  brief,  are  not  known  but  are  used;  they  do 
not  belong  to  the  plane  of  the  actual  but  to  the  realm  of 
values.    "A  deity,"  says  King,  "  is  a  symbol,  more  or  less  per 
sonal  in  form,  of  a  value  or  values  which  have  arisen  in  the  ex 
perience  of  some  individual  person  or  people."  3    Let  us  grant 
that  man  may  not  worship  the  merely  actual,  that  religion  by 
its  very  nature  involves  a  reference  to  human  needs  and  as 
pirations.    But  is  not  the  religious  object  regarded  by  the  re 
ligious  consciousness  both  as  genuinely  objective  and  as  no 
less  truly  existent  than  any  reality  which  may  be  mentioned  ? 
Deprive  the  religious  object  of  actuality,  furthermore,  and 
does  it  not  lose  that  which  makes  it  social  in  character?    Ex 
cept  in  the  realm  of  the  actual,  how  may  an  object  be  one 
which  is  shared  in  common,  while  nevertheless  differing  from 
such  entities  as  moral  or  aesthetic  norms  in  that  the  relations 
between  it  and  human  individuals  are  social?     The  func 
tional  standpoint,  therefore,  leads  quite  naturally  to  the 
insistence  that  religious  experience  does  not,  or  at  least  need 
not,  involve  a  social  relation  between  worshipper  and  deity. 
Says  Ames,  "It  is  as  possible  to  have  prayer  which  is  not 
prayer  'to'  some  person  or  thing,  as  to  have  sacrifice  which 

1  Cf.  The  Development  of  Religion,  pp.  236  and  237. 

2  For  a  contrasting  view  which  at  the  same  time  discloses  with  greater 
completeness  the  motives  fundamental  to  ideas  of  great  unseen  beings, 
see  Leuba,  A  Psychological  Study  of  Religion,  pp.  86ff.,  particularly  pp. 
96ff.,  and  Stratton,  The  Psychology  of  the  Religious  Life,  pp.  314^;  com 
pare  with  Wundt,  Elements  of  Folk  Psychology,  pp.  93f. 

3  The  Development  of  Religion,  p.  261. 


356  PHILOSOPHICAL  ESSAYS 

is  not  sacrifice  'to'  some  person  or  thing."  l  Far  truer  than 
this  to  experience  are  the  repeated  assertions  of  Miss  Strong 
to  the  effect  that  "prayer  is  the  direct  interaction  of  two 
selves  arising  simultaneously  in  consciousness;"  "it  is  a 
relation  of  selves,  and  aims  at  the  production  of  another 
self;"  as  is  universal  in  the  relations  between  selves,  more 
over,  there  are  two  phases  of  prayer, — the  practical  concern 
for  strength,  inspiration,  and  the  insight  necessary  for  the 
bearing  of  burdens  and  the  performance  of  tasks,  and  also 
the  aesthetic  interest  expressed  in  a  "contemplative  sharing 
of  the  life  of  a  larger  self,"  in  "the  enjoyment  of  God,  as  an 
end  in  itself."  2 

Thus  we  are  forced  to  the  conclusion  that  those  functional 
interpretations  which,  under  the  influence  of  biological  and 
evolutionary  conceptions,  interpret  religious  experience  in 
terms  of  its  setting  in  the  life-process,  of  adjustment,  or  of 
practical  control,  so  impoverish  and  enslave  mind  as  to  be 
inadequate  as  accounts,  not  merely  of  the  nature  and  genesis 
of  religion  and  of  the  course  of  its  development,  but  also  of 
certain  of  the  social  characteristics  which  religion  must  be 
conceded  to  possess. 

1  The  Psychology  of  Religious  Experience.,  p.  141. 

2  The  Psychology  of  Prayer,  pp.  24,  25,  90,  and  96,  respectively.    The 
fact  that  we  have  quoted  these  passages  does  not  imply  an  endorsement 
of  the  method  employed  in  the  essay.    The  very  approach  that  is  taken 
seems  to  lead  to  a  degree  of  confusion.    We  read:  "Any  self  which  we 
know  and  distinguish  from  other  things  is  not  something  which  has  con 
sciousness  .  .  .  but  something  which  arises  in  consciousness,"  and  fol 
lowing  this  is  the  statement  that  "the  consciousness  in  which  it  arises 
is  of  a  social  type"  (p.  18).    But,  the  reader  will  at  once  ask,  is  it  not  the 
selves  which  arise  within  consciousness  that  should  be  described  as  social, 
rather  than  the  consciousness  within  which  they  both  arise?    And,  indeed, 
the  writer  herself  implies  this  when  she  says  that  "consciousness  begins 
in  the  child"  and  that  "he  attains  self-consciousness  through  personal 
relations"  (p.  19,  italics  mine).     After  being  thus  told  that  the  child 
himself  attains  to  consciousness  and  to  self-consciousness,  we  are  dis 
turbed  to  learn  that  "the  selves  which  enter  into  relation    ...  are  mental 
facts,  states  of  consciousness.    It  is  an  idea  of  myself  and  an  idea  of  you 
which  relate  themselves  in  such  a  way  as  to  produce  a  new  self"  (p.  20). 
Similarly,  prayer,  though  described  as  a  relation  between  selves,  becomes 
at  times  but  a  relation  between  two  ideas  of  selves. 


Printed  in  the  United  States  of  America 


^_ 

a 

i 

1 

03 

cd 

1-3 

CH 

a 

O 

^ 

£H 

0 

O 

K 

O 

0 
CQ 

S     'c 

O 

^ 

fft 

w 

•^1 

2 

s 

• 

rH             CO 

<c 
S5 

""  ' 

cd 

^. 

CO 

Cfi 

W 

JL 

CD 

0 

H 

cd 

o1 

o 

•H 

cd 

"a,    • 

cd 

o  a 

CO     O 

O 

0   -P 

H  -d 

tug 

w 

^ 

o 

^ 

Q 

H 

o  *o 

CV2 

H  CO 

*, 

•H    C£) 

X!  LO 

i 

University  of  Toronto 
Library 


DO  NOT 

REMOVE 

THE 

CARD 

FROM 

THIS 

POCKET 


Acme  Library  Card  Pocket 

Under  Pat.  "Ref.  Index  File" 
Made  by  LIBRARY  BUREAU