Skip to main content

Full text of "International Congress of Arts and Sciences"

See other formats


BOOK    060. IN8    V.  1    c.  1 
INTERNATIONAL    CONGRESS    OF    ARTS 
AND    SCIENCES    #    INTERNATIONAL    CONG 


3    T1S3    00057781    T 


^ 


THIS  FIRST  EDITION  DE  LUXE, 

printed  from  type,  is  limited  to  five  hundred 

sets,  of  which  this  is  copy 

No s-..r^^ 


INTERNATIONAL   CONGRESS 

OF  ARTS  AND  SCIENCE 

. ^ 


Digitized  by  tine  Internet  Archive 

in  2010  with  funding  from 

Boston  Library  Consortium  IVIember  Libraries 


http://www.archive.org/details/internationalcon01cong 


R 


INTERNATIONAL  CONGRESS 

OF 

ARTS  AND  SCIENCE 


EDITED  BY 

Howard  J.  Rogers,  A.M.,  LL.D. 


DIRECTOR  OF  CONGRESSES 


VOLUME  I 

HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

By  THE  Editor 

SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF  THE  CONGRESS 
By  Professor  Hugo  Munsterberg 

PHILOSOPHY  AND  MATHEMATICS 


V' 


UNIVERSITY  ALLIANCE 

LONDON  NEW  YORK 


Copyright  igo6  by  Houghton,  Mifflin  &  Co. 

all  rights  reserved 

Copyright  iqo8  by  University  Alliance 


Si 

ILLUSTRATIONS 


VOLUME  I 

FACING 
PAGE 

XMA    Mater Frontispiece 

^  Photogravure  from  the  statue  by  Daniel  C.  French 


Dr.    Howard   J.    Rogers 1 

Photogravure  from  a  photograph 

Dr.  Simon  Newcomb 135 

Photogravure  from  a  photograph 

Dr.  Benno  Erdmann 352 

Photogravure  from  a  photograph 


Portraits  of  Dr.  Charles  Emile  Picard,  Dr.  Heinrich  Maschke  and 

Dr.  E.  H.  Moore 452 

Photogravure  from  a  photograph 


ORGANIZATION  OF  THE  CONGRESS 


PRESIDENT  OF  THE  EXPOSITION: 
HON.  DAVID   R.  FRANCIS,  A.M.,  LL.D. 

DIRECTOR  OF  CONGRESSES: 

HOWARD   J.  ROGERS,  A.M.,  LL.D. 

Universal  Exposition,  1904. 


ADMINISTRATIVE  BOARD 

NICHOLAS  MURRAY   BUTLER;  Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

President  of  Columbia  University,  Chairman. 

WILLIAM   R.   HARPER,  Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

President  of  the  University  of  Chicago. 

R.   H.  JESSE,   Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

President  of  the  University  of  Missouri. 

HENRY   S.   PRITCHETT,  Ph.D.,  LL.D. 
President  of  the  Massachusetts  Institute  of  Technology. 

HERBERT   PUTNAM,  Litt.D.,  LL.D. 
Librarian  of  Congress. 

FREDERICK   J.   V.   SKIFF,  A.M. 

Director  of  the  Field  Columbian  Museum. 


OFFICERS   OF  THE   CONGRESS 

PRESIDENT: 
SIMON   NEWCOMB,   Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

Retired  Professor  U.  S.  N. 

VICE-PRESIDENTS: 

HUGO   MUNSTERBERG,   Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

Professor  of  Psychology  in  Harvard  University. 

ALBION  W.  SMALL,  Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

Professor  of  Sociology  in  the  University  of  Chicago. 


TABLE  OF   CONTENTS 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

Howard  J.  Rogers,  A.M.,  LL.D. 

Programme 

Purpose  and  Plan  of  the  Congress  . 
Organization  of  the  Congress    . 
Officers  of  the  Congress 
Speakers  and  Chairmen 
Chronological  Order  of  Proceedings 
Programme  of  Social  Events     .     •  . 
List  of  Ten-Minute  Speakers 

THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

Hugo  Munsterberg,  Ph.D.,  LL.D, 


47 
50 
52 
53 
54 
77 
81 
82 

85 


PROCEEDINGS  OF   THE  CONGRESS 

Introductory  Address. 

The  Evolution  of  the  Scientific  Investigator        .        .        .        .        .         .     135 

Simon  Newcomb,  Ph.D.,  LL.D, 

Division  A  —  Normative  Science. 

The  Sciences  of  the  Ideal 151 

Professor  Josiah  Roycb. 

Department  I  —  Philosophy. 

Chairman's  Address 171 

Professor  Borden  P.  Bowne. 

Philosophy:  Its  Fundamental  Conceptions  and  its  Methods  .        .173 

Professor  George  Holmes  Howison. 

The  Development  of  Philosophy  in  the  Nineteenth  Century  .         .         .     194 

Professor  George  Trumbull  Ladd. 

Section  A  —  Metaphysics. 

The  Relations  between  Metaphysics  and  the  Other  Sciences         .        .        .     227 
Professor  Alfred  Edward  Taylor. 

The  Present  Problems  of  Metaphysics 246 

Professor  Alexander  Thomas  Ormond, 
Short  Papers _     259 

Section  B  —  Philosophy  op  Religion. 

The  Relation  of  the  Philosophy  of  Religion  to  the  Other  Sciences  .    263 

Professor  Otto  Pfleiderer. 


viii  TABLE  OF   CONTENTS 

Main  Problems  of  the  Philosophy  of  Religion:   Psychology  and  Theory  of 
Knowledge  in  the  Science  of  Religion      .......     275 

Professor  Ernst  Troeltsch. 

Short  Papers 289 

Section  C  —  Logic. 

The  Relations  of  Logic  to  Other  Disciplines        .         .         .         .         .         .296 

Professor  William  Alexander  Hammond. 

The  Field  of  Logic •      .         .313 

Professor  Frederick  J.  E.  Woodbridge. 

Section  D  —  Methodology  of  Science. 

On  the  Theory  of  Science  .........     333 

Professor  Wilhelm  Ostwald. 

The  Content  and  Validity  of  the  Causal  Law      ......     353 

Professor  Benno  Erdmann. 

Section  E  —  Ethics. 

The  Relations  of  Ethics 391 

Professor  William  Ritchie  Sorley. 

Problems  of  Ethics 403 

Professor  Paul  Hensel. 

Section  F  —  Esthetics. 

The  Relation  of  Esthetics  to  Psychology  and  Philosophy    .         .         .         .417 
Professor  Henry  Rutgers  Marshall. 

The  Fundamental  Questions  of  Contemporary  Esthetics     ....     434 
Professor  Max  Dessoir. 

Special  Bibliography  prepared  by  Professor  Dessoir  for  his  Address    .         .447 

Short  Papers    . 448 

General  Bibliography  for  Department  of  Philosophy 449 

Department  II  —  Mathematics. 

The  Fundamental  Conceptions  and  Methods  of  Mathematics       .         .         .     456 
Professor  Maxime  Bocher. 

The  History  of  Mathematics  in  the  Nineteenth  Century       .         .         .         .     474 
Professor  James  P.  Pierpont. 

Section  A  —  Algebra  and  Analysis. 

On  the  Development  of  Mathematical  Analysis  and  its  Relations  to  Some 

Other  Sciences    ...........     497 

Professor  Emile  Picard. 

On  Present  Problems  of  Algebra  and  Analysis   ......     518 

Professor  Heinrich  Maschke. 

Short  Papers •     531 


TABLE  OF   CONTENTS  ix 

Section  B  —  Geometry. 

A  Study  of  the  Development  of  Geometric  Methods 535 

M.  Jean  Gaston  Darboux. 

The  Present  Problems  of  Geometry     ........     559 

Dr.  Edward  Kasner. 

Short  Papers 587 

Section  C  —  Applied  Mathematics. 

The  Relations  of  Applied  Mathematics 591 

Professor  Ludwig  Boltzmann. 

The  Principles  of  Mathematical  Physics    .......     604 

Professor  Henri  Poincare. 

General  Bibliography  of  the  Department  of  Mathematics     ....     623 

Special  Bibliography  accompanying  Professor  Boltzmann' s  Address    .         .     625 

CONTENTS  OF  THE  SERIES .        .627 


CONGRESS  OF  ARTS  AND  SCIENCE 


■  ■■       -    :, _. 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE   CONGRESS 

BY  HOWARD  J.  ROGERS   A.M.,  LL.D. 

The  forces  which  bring  to  a  common  point  the  thousandfold  energies 
of  a  universal  exposition  can  best  promote  an  international  congress 
of  ideas.  Under  national  patronage  and  under  the  spur  of  interna- 
tional competition  the  best  products  and  the  latest  inventions  of 
man  in  science,  in  literature,  and  in  art  are  grouped  together  in  orderly- 
classification.  Whether  the  motive  underlying  the  exhibits  be  the 
promotion  of  commerce  and  trade,  or  whether  it  be  individual 
ambition,  or  whether  it  be  national  pride  and  loyalty,  the  resultant 
is  the  same.  The  space  within  the  boundaries  of  the  exposition  is 
a  forum  of  the  nations  where  equal  rights  are  guaranteed  to  every 
representative  from  any  quarter  of  the  globe,  and  where  the  sover- 
eignty of  each  nation  is  recognized  whenever  its  flag  floats  over  a 
national  pavilion  or  an  exhibit  area.  The  productive  genius  of  every 
governed  people  contends  in  peaceful  rivalry  for  world  recognition, 
and  the  exposition  becomes  an  international  clearing-house  for 
practical  ideas. 

For  the  demonstration  of  the  value  of  these  products  men  thor- 
oughly skilled  in  their  development  and  use  are  sent  by  the  various 
exhibitors.  The  exposition  by  the  logic  of  its  creation  thus  gathers 
to  itself  the  expert  representatives  of  every  art  and  industry.  For 
at  least  two  months  in  the  exposition  period  there  are  present  the 
members  of  the  international  jury  of  awards,  selected  specially  by 
the  different  governments  for  their  thorough  knowledge,  theoretical 
and  practical,  of  the  departments  to  which  they  are  assigned,  and 
selected  further  for  their  ability  to  impress  upon  others  the  correct- 
ness of  their  views.  The  renown  of  a  universal  exposition  brings,  as 
visitors,  students  and  investigators  bent  upon  the  solution  of  prob- 
lems and  anxious  to  know  the  latest  contributions  to  the  facts  and 
the  theories  which  underlie  every  phase  of  the  world's  development. 

The  material  therefore  is  ready  at  hand  with  which  to  construct 
the  framework  of  a  conference  of  parts,  or  a  congress  of  the  whole 
of  any  subject.  It  was  a  natural  and  logical  step  to  accompany  the 
study  of  the  exhibits  with  a  debate  on  their  excellence,  an  analysis 
of  their  growth,  and  an  .argument  for  their  future.  Hence  the  con- 
gress. The  exposition  and  the  congress  are  correlative  terms.  The 
former  concentres  the  visible  products  of  the  brain  and  hand  of  man ; 
the  congress  is  the  literary  embodiment  of  its  activities. 


2  THE  HISTORY   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

Yet  it  was  not  till  the  Paris  Exposition  of  1889  that  the  idea  of 
a  series  of  congresses,  international  in  membership  and  universal  in 
scope,  was  fully  developed.  The  three  preceding  expositions,  Paris, 
1878,  Philadelphia,  1876,  and  Vienna,  1873,  had  held  under  their 
auspices  many  conferences  and  congresses,  and  indeed  the  germ  of 
the  congress  idea  may  be  said  to  have  been  the  establishment  of  the 
International  Scientific  Commission  in  connection  with  the  Paris 
Exposition  of  1867;  but  all  of  these  meetings  were  unrelated  and 
sometimes  almost  accidental  in  their  organization,  although  many 
were  of  great  scientific  interest  and  value. 

The  success  of  the  series  of  seventy  congresses  in  Paris  in  1889 
led  the  authorities  of  the  World's  Columbian  Exposition  in  1893 
to  establish  the  World's  Congress  Auxiliary  designed  "to  supple- 
ment the  exhibit  of  material  progress  by  the  Exposition,  by  a  por- 
trayal of  the  wonderful  achievements  of  the  new  age  in  science, 
literature,  education,  government,  jurisprudence,  morals,  charity, 
religion,  and  other  departments  of  human  activity,  as  the  most 
effective  means  of  increasing  the  fraternity,  progress,  prosperity, 
and  peace  of  mankind."  The  widespread  interest  in  this  series  of 
meetings  is  a  matter  easily  within  recollection,  but  they  were  in 
no  wise  interrelated  to  each  other,  nor  more  than  ordinarily  com- 
prehensive in  their  scope. 

It  remained  for  the  Paris  Exposition  of  1900  to  bring  to  a  perfect 
organization  this  type  of  congress  development.  By  ministerial 
decree  issued  two  years  prior  to  the  exposition  the  conduct  of  the 
department  was  set  forth  to  the  minutest  detail.  One  hundred 
twenty-five  congresses,  each  with  its  separate  secretary  and  organiz- 
ing committee,  were  authorized  and  grouped  under  twelve  sections 
corresponding  closely  to  the  exhibit  classification.  The  principal 
delegate,  M.  Gariel,  reported  to  a  special  commission,  which  was 
directly  responsible  to  the  government.  The  department  was  ad- 
mirably conducted  and  reached  as  high  a  degree  of  success  as  a  highly 
diversified,  ably  administered,  but  unrelated  system  of  international 
conferences  could.  And  yet  the  attendance  on  a  majority  of  these 
congresses  was  disappointing,  and  in  many  there  was  scarcely  any 
one  present  outside  the  immediate  circle  of  those  concerned  in  its 
development.  If  this  condition  could  prevail  in  Paris,  the  home  of 
arts  and  letters,  in  the  immediate  centre  of  the  great  constituency 
of  the  University  and  of  many  scientific  circles  and  learned  societies, 
and  within  easy  traveling  distance  of  other  European  university 
and  literary  centres,  it  was  fair  to  presume  that  the  usefulness  of  this 
class  of  congress  was  decreasing.  It  certainly  was  safe  to  assume, 
on  the  part  of  the  authorities  of  the  St.  Louis  Exposition  of  1904, 
that  such  a  series  could  not  be  a  success  in  that  city,  owing  to  its 
geographical  position  and  the  limited  number  of  university  and 


THE  HISTORY   OF   THE   CONGRESS  3 

scientific  circles  within  a  reasonable  traveling  distance.  Something 
more  than  a  repetition  of  the  stereotyped  form  of  conference  was 
admitted  to  be  necessary  in  order  to  arouse  interest  among  scholars 
and  to  bring  credit  to  the  Exposition. 

This  was  the  serious  problem  which  confronted  the  Exposition  of 
St.  Louis.  No  exposition  was  ever  better  fitted  to  serve  as  the  ground- 
work of  a  congress  of  ideas  than  that  of  St.  Louis.  The  ideal  of  the 
Exposition,  which  was  created  in  time  and  fixed  in  place  to  com- 
memorate a  great  historic  event,  was  its  educational  influence.  Its 
appeal  to  the  citizens  of  the  United  States  for  support,  to  the  Federal 
Congress  for  appropriations,  and  to  foreign  governments  for  coopera- 
tion, was  made  purely  on  this  basis.  For  the  first  time  in  the  history 
of  expositions  the  educational  influence  was  made  the  dominant 
factor  and  the  classification  and  installation  of  exhibits  made  con- 
tributory to  that  principle.  The  main  purpose  of  the  Exposition  was 
to  place  within  reach  of  the  investigator  the  objective  thought  of 
the  world,  so  classified  as  to  show  its  relations  to  all  similar  phases 
of  human  endeavor,  and  so  arranged  as  to  be  practically  available 
for  reference  and  study.  As  a  part  of  the  organic  scheme  a  congress 
plan  was  contemplated  which  should  be  correlative  with  the  exhibit 
features  of  the  Exposition,  and  whose  published  proceedings  should 
stand  as  a  monument  to  the  breadth  and  enterprise  of  the  Exposition 
long  after  its  buildings  had  disappeared  and  its  commercial  achieve- 
ments grown  dim  in  the  minds  of  men. 

DEVELOPMENT  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

The  Department  of  Congresses,  to  which  was  to  be  intrusted  this 
difficult  task,  was  not  formed  until  the  latter  part  of  1902,  although 
the  question  was  for  a  year  previous  the  subject  of  many  discussions 
and  conferences  between  the  President  of  the  Exposition,  Mr. 
Francis;  the  Director  of  Exhibits,  Mr.  Skiff;  the  Chief  of  the  Depart- 
ment of  Education,  Mr.  Rogers;  President  Nicholas  Murray  Butler 
of  Columbia  University,  and  President  William  R.  Harper  of  Chicago 
University.  To  the  disinterested  and  valuable  advice  of  the  two  last- 
named  gentlemen  during  the  entire  history  of  the  Congress  the  Ex- 
position is  under  heavy  obligations.  During  this  period  proposals  had 
been  made  to  two  men  of  international  reputation  to  give  all  their 
time  for  two  years  to  the  organization  of  a  plan  of  congresses  which 
should  accomplish  the  ultimate  purpose  of  the  Exposition  authorities. 
Neither  one,  however,  could  arrange  to  be  relieved  of  the  pressure  of 
his  regular  duties,  and  the  entire  scheme  of  supervision  was  conse- 
quently changed.  The  plan  adopted  was  based  upon  the  idea  of  an 
advisory  board  composed  of  men  of  high  literary  and  scientific 
standing  who  should  consider  and  recommend  the  kind  of  congress 
most  worthy  of  promotion,  and  the  details  of  its  development. 


4  THE  HISTORY   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

In  November,  1902,  Howard  J.  Rogers,  LL.D.,  was  appointed 
Director  of  Congresses,  and  the  members  of  the  Advisory  (afterwards 
termed  Administrative)  Board  selected  as  follows:  — 

Chairman:  Nicholas  Murray  Butler,  Ph.D.,  LL.D.,  President 
Columbia  University. 

William  R.  Harper,  Ph.D.,  LL.D.,  President  University  of 
Chicago. 

Honorable  Frederick  W.  Holls,  A.M.,  LL.B.,  New  York. 

R.  H.  Jesse,  Ph.D.,  LL.D.,  President  University  of  Missouri. 

Henry  S.  Pritchett,  Ph.D.,  LL.D.,  President  Massachusetts 
Institute  of  Technology. 

Herbert  Putnam,  Litt.D.,  LLD.,  Librarian  of  Congress. 

Frederick  J.  V.  Skiff,  A.M.,  Director  of  Field  Columbian  Mu- 
seum. 

The  action  of  the  Executive  Committee  of  the  Exposition,  ap- 
proved by  the  President,  was  as  follows :  — 

There  shall  be  appointed  by  the  President  of  the  Exposition  Company  a 
Director  of  Congresses  who  shall  report  to  the  President  of  the  Exposition  Com- 
pany. 

There  shall  be  appointed  by  the  President  of  the  Exposition  Company  an 
Advisory  Board  of  seven  persons,  the  chairman  to  be  named  by  the  President, 
who  shaU  meet  at  the  call  of  the  Director  of  Congresses,  or  the  Chairman  of  the 
Advisory  Board. 

The  expenses  of  the  members  of  the  Advisory  Board  while  on  business  of  the 
Exposition  shall  be  a  charge  against  the  funds  of  the  Exposition  Company. 

The  duties  of  the  said  Advisory  Board  shall  be:  to  consider  and  make  recom- 
mendations to  the  Director  of  Congresses  on  all  matters  submitted  to  them;  to 
determine  the  number  and  the  extent  of  the  congresses;  the  emphasis  to  be 
placed  upon  special  features;  the  prominent  men  to  be  invited  to  participate; 
the  character  of  the  programmes;  and  the  methods  for  successfully  carrying  out 
the  enterprise. 

There  shall  be  set  aside  from  the  Exposition  funds  for  the  maintenance  of  the 
congresses  the  sum  of  two  hundred  thousand  dollars  ($200,000). 

The  standing  Committee  on  Congresses  from  the  Exposition  board 
of  directors  was  shortly  afterwards  appointed  and  was  composed  of 
five  of  the  most  prominent  men  in  St.  Louis :  — 

Chairman:    Hon.  Frederick  W.  Lehmann,  Attorney  at  Law. 

Breckenridge  Jones,  Banker. 

Charles  W.  Knapp,  Editor  of  The  St  Louis  Republic. 

John  Schroers,  Manager  of  the  Westliche  Post. 

A.  F.  Shapleigh,  Merchant. 

To  this  committee  were  referred  for  consideration  by  the  President 
all  matters  of  policy  submitted  by  the  Director  of  Congresses.  This 
committee  had  jurisdiction  over  all  congress  matters,  including  not 
only  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science,  but  also  the  many  miscel- 
laneous congresses  and  conventions,  and  a  great  part  of  the  success 


THE   HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS  5 

of  the  congresses  is  due  to  their  broad-minded  and  liberal  deter- 
mination of  the  questions  laid  before  them. 

IDEA    OF   THE    CONGRESS    OF   ARTS   AND    SCIENCE 

It  is  impossible  to  ascribe  the  original  idea  of  the  Congress  of 
Arts  and  Science  to  any  one  person.  It  was  a  matter  of  slow  growth 
from  the  many  conferences  which  had  been  held  for  a  year  by  men 
of  many  occupations,  and  as  finally  worked  out  bore  little  resemblance 
to  the  original  plans  under  discussion.  The  germ  of  the  idea  may  fairly 
be  said  to  have  been  contained  in  Director  Skiff's  insistence  to  the 
Executive  Committee  of  the  Exposition  that  the  congress  work 
stand  for  something  more  than  an  unrelated  series  of  independent 
gatherings,  and  that  some  project  be  authorized  which  would  at  once 
be  distinctive  and  of  real  scientific  worth.  To  support  this  view 
Director  Skiff  brought  the  Executive  Committee  to  the  view  of 
expending  $200,000,  if  need  be,  to  insure  the  project.  Starting  from 
this  suggestion  many  plans  were  brought  forward,  but  one  which 
seems  to  belong  of  right  to  the  late  Honorable  Frederick  W.  Holls, 
of  New  York  City,  contained  perhaps  the  next  recognizable  step  in 
advance.  This  thought  was,  briefly,  that  a  series  of  lectures  on 
scientific  and  literary  topics  by  men  prominent  in  their  respective 
fields  be  delivered  at  the  Exposition  and  that  the  Exposition  pay 
the  speakers  for  their  services.  This  point  was  thoroughly  discussed 
by  Mr.  Holls  and  President  Butler,  and  the  next  step  in  the  evolution 
of  the  Congress  was  the  idea  of  bringing  these  lecturers  together  at 
the  Exposition  at  about  the  same  time  or  all  during  one  month.  At 
this  stage  Professor  Hugo  Miinsterberg,  who  was  the  guest  of  Mr. 
Holls  and  an  invited  participant  in  the  conference,  made  the  import- 
ant suggestion  that  such  a  series  of  unrelated  lectures,  even  though 
given  by  most  eminent  men,  would  have  little  or  no  scientific  value, 
but  that  if  some  relation,  or  underlying  thought,  could  be  intro- 
duced into  the  addresses,  then  the  best  work  could  be  done,  which 
would  be  of  real  value  to  the  scientific  world.  He  further  stated  that 
only  in  this  case  would  scientific  leaders  be  likely  to  favor  the  plan 
of  a  St.  Louis  congress,  as  they  would  feel  attracted  not  so  much 
through  the  honorariums  to  be  given  for  their  services  as  through 
the  valuable  opportunity  of  developing  such  a  contribution  to  scien- 
tific thought.  Subsequently  Professor  Miinsterberg  was  asked  by 
Mr.  Holls  to  formulate  his  ideas  in  a  manner  to  be  submitted  to  the 
Exposition  authorities.  This  was  done  in  a  communication  under 
date  of  October  20,  1902,  which  contained  logically  presented  the 
foundation  of  the  plan  afterwards  worked  out  in  detail.  At  this 
juncture  the  Department  of  Congresses  was  organized,  as  has  been 
stated,  the  Director  named,  and  the  Administrative  Board  appointed, 
and  on  December  27,  1902,  the  first  meeting  of  the  Director  with 
the  Administrative  Board  took  place  in  New  York  City. 


6  THE   HISTORY   OF   THE   CONGRESS 

A  thorough  canvass  of  the  subject  was  made  at  this  meeting  and 
as  a  result  the  following  recommendations  were  made  to  the  Exposi- 
tion authorities :  — 

(1)  That  the  sessions  of  this  Congress  be  held  within  a  period 
of  four  weeks,  beginning  September  15,  1904. 

(2)  That  the  various  groups  of  learned  men  who  may  come  together 
be  asked  to  discuss  their  several  sciences  or  professions  with  reference 
to  some  theme  of  universal  human  interest,  in  order  that  thereby 
a  certain  unity  of  interest  and  of  action  may  be  had.  Under  such  a 
plan  the  groups  of  men  who  come  together  would  thus  form  sections 
of  a  single  Congress  rather  than  separate  congresses. 

(3)  As  a  subject  which  has  universal  significance,  and  one  likely 
to  serve  as  a  connecting  thread  for  all  of  the  discussions  of  the  Con- 
gress, the  theme  "The  Progress  of  Man  since  the  Louisiana  Pur- 
chase" was  considered  by  the  Administrative  Board  fit  and  suggest- 
ive. It  is  believed  that  discussions  by  leaders  of  thought  in  the 
various  branches  of  pure  and  applied  science,  in  philosophy,  in  politics, 
and  in  religion,  from  the  standpoint  of  man's  progress  in  the  century 
which  has  elapsed,  would  be  fruitful,  not  only  in  clearing  the  thoughts 
of  men  not  trained  in  science  and  in  government,  but  also  in  preparing 
the  way  for  new  advances. 

(4)  The  Administrative  Board  further  recommends  that  the  Con- 
gress be  made  up  from  men  of  thought  and  of  action,  whose  work 
would  probably  fall  under  the  following  general  heads :  — 

a.  The  Natural  Sciences  (such  as  Astronomy,  Biology,  Mathe- 
matics, etc.). 

h.  The  Historical,  Sociological,  and  Economic  group  of  studies 
(History,  Political  Economy,  etc.). 

c.  Philosophy  and  Religion. 

d.  Medicine  and  Surgery. 

e.  Law,  Politics,  and  Government  (including  development  and 
history  of  the  colonies,  their  government,  revenue  and  prosperity, 
arbitration,  etc.). 

/.  Applied  Science  (including  the  various  branches  of  engineer- 
ing). 

(5)  The  Administrative  Board  recommends  further  referring  to 
a  special  committee  cf  seven  the  problem  of  indicating  in  detail  the 
method  in  which  this  plan  can  best  be  carried  out.  To  this  com- 
mittee is  assigned  the  duty  of  choosing  the  general  divisions  of  the 
Congress,  the  various  branches  of  science  and  of  study  in  these  divi- 
sions, and  of  recommending  to  the  Administrative  Board  a  detailed 
plan  of  the  sections  in  which,  in  their  judgment,  those  who  come  to 
the  Congress  maybe  most  effectively  grouped,  with  a  view  not  only 
to  bring  out  the  central  theme,  but  also  to  represent  in  a  helpful  way 
and  in  a  suggestive  manner  the  present  boundary  of  knowledge  in  the 


THE  HISTORY   OF   THE   CONGRESS  7 

various  lines  of  study  and  investigation  which  the  committee  may 
think  wise  to  accept. 

These  recommendations  were  transmitted  by  the  Director  of 
Congresses  to  the  Committee  on  Congresses,  approved  by  them,  and 
afterwards  approved  by  the  Executive  Committee  and  the  President. 
The  first  four  recommendations  were  of  a  preliminary  character,  but 
the  fifth  contained  a  distinct  advance  in  the  formation  of  a  Committee 
on  Plan  and  Scope  which  should  be  composed  of  eminent  scientists 
capable  of  developing  the  fundamental  idea  into  a  plan  which  should 
harmonize  with  the  scientific  work  in  every  field.  The  committee 
selected  were  as  follows :  — 

De.  Simon  Newcomb,  Ph.D.,  LL.D.,  Retired  Professor  of  Mathe- 
matics, U.  S.  Navy. 

Prof.  Hugo  Munsterberg,  Ph.D.,  LL.D.,  Professor  of  Psycho- 
logy, Harvard  University. 

Prof.  John  Bassett  Moore,  LL.D.,  ex-assistant  Secretary  of 
State,  and  Professor  of  International  Law  and  Diplomacy,  Columbia 
University. 

Prof.  Albion  W.  Small,  Ph.D.,  Professor  of  Sociology,  Uni- 
versity of  Chicago. 

Dr.  William  H.  Welch,  M.D.,  LL.D.,  Professor  of  Pathology, 
Johns  Hopkins  University. 

Hon.  Elihu  Thomson,  Consulting  Engineer  General  Electric 
Company. 

Prof.  George  F.  Moore,  D.D.,  LL.D.,  Professor  of  Comparative 
Religion,  Harvard  University. 

In  response  to  a  letter  from  President  Butler,  Chairman  of  the 
Administrative  Board,  giving  a  complete  resume  of  the  growth  of 
the  idea  of  the  Congress  to  that  time,  all  of  the  members  of  the  com- 
mittee, with  the  exception  of  Mr.  Thomson,  met  at  the  Hotel  Man- 
hattan on  January  10,  1903,  for  a  prehminary  discussion.  The  entire 
field  was  canvassed,  using  the  recommendations  of  the  Administrative 
Board  and  the  aforementioned  letter  of  Professor  Miinsterberg's  to 
Mr.  HoUs  as  a  basis,  and  an  adjournment  taken  until  January  17 
for  the  preparation  of  detailed  recommendations. 

The  Committee  on  Plan  and  Scope  again  met,  all  members  being 
present,  at  the  Hotel  Manhattan  on  January  17,  and  arrived  at 
definite  conclusions,  which  were  embodied  in  the  report  to  the 
Administrative  Board,  a  meeting  of  which  had  been  called  at  the 
Hotel  Manhattan  for  January  19,  1903.  The  report  of  the  Com- 
mittee on  Plan  and  Scope  is  of  such  historic  importance  in  the  devel- 
opment of  the  Congress  that  it  is  given  as  follows,  although  many 
points  were  afterwards  materially  modified  :  — ■ 


8  THE  HISTORY   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

New  York,  January  19,  1903. 
President  Nicholas  Murray  Butler, 

Chairman  Administrative  Board  of  World's  Congress  at 
The  Louisiana  Purchase  Exposition: 

Dear  Sir,  —  The  undersigned,  appointed  by  your  Board  a  committee  on  the 
scope  and  plan  of  the  proposed  World's  Congress,  at  the  Louisiana  Purchase 
Exposition,  have  the  honor  to  submit  the  following  report:  — 

The  authority  under  which  the  Committee  acted  is  found  in  a  commimication 
addressed  to  its  members  by  the  Chairman  of  the  Administrative  Board.  A 
subsequent  commimication  to  the  Chairman  of  the  Committee  indicated  that  the 
widest  scope  was  allowed  to  it  in  preparing  its  plan.  Under  this  authority  the 
Committee  met  on  January  10,  1903,  and  again  on  January  17.  The  Committee 
was,, from  the  beginning,  unanimous  in  accepting  the  general  plan  of  the  Admin- 
istrative Board,  that  there  should  be  but  a  single  congress,  which,  however,  might 
be  divided  and  subdivided,  in  accord  with  the  general  plan,  into  divisions,  depart- 
ments, and  sections,  as  its  deliberations  proceed. 

PLANS    OF   THE    CONGRESS 

As  a  basis  of  discussion  two  plans  were  drawn  up  by  members  of  the  Committee 
and  submitted  to  it.  The  one,  by  Professor  Miinsterberg,  started  from  a  compre- 
hensive classification  and  review  of  human  achievement  in  advancing  knowledge, 
the  other,'  by  Professor  Small,  from  an  equally  comprehensive  review  of  the  great 
public  questions  involved  in  human  progress. 

Professor  Miinsterberg  proposed  a  congress  having  the  definite  task  of  bringing 
out  the  unity  of  knowledge  with  a  view  of  correlating  the  scattered  theoretical  and 
practical  scientific  work  of  our  day.  This  plan  proposed  that  the  congress  should 
continue  through  one  week.  The  first  day  was  to  be  devoted  to  the  discussion  of 
the  most  general  problem  of  knowledge  in  one  comprehensive  discussion  and  four 
general  divisions.  On  the  second  day  the  congress  was  to  divide  into  several 
groups  and  on  the  remaining  days  into  yet  more  specialized  groups,  as  set  forth 
in  detail  in  the  plan. 

The  plan  by  Professor  Small  proposed  a  congress  which  would  exhibit  not 
merely  the  scholar's  interpretation  of  progress  in  scholarship,  but  rather  the 
scholar's  interpretation  of  progress  in  civilization  in  general.    The  proposal  was 
based  on  a  division  of  human  interests  into  six  great  groups:  — 
I.    The  Promotion  of  Health. 
II.   The  Production  of  Wealth. 

III.  The  Harmonizing  of  Human  Relations. 

IV.  Discovery  and  Spread  of  Knowledge. 
V.    Progress  in  the  Fine  Arts. 

VI.    Progress  in  Religion. 

The  plan  agreed  with  the  other  in  beginning  with  a  general  discussion  and  then 
subdividing  the"  congress  into  divisions  and  groups. 

As  a  third  plan  the  Chairman  of  the  Committee  suggested  the  idea  of  a  congress 
of  publicists  and  representative  men  of  all  nations  and  of  all  civilized  peoples, 
which  should  discuss  relations  of  each  to  all  the  others  and  throw  light  on  the 
question  of  promoting  the  unity  and  progress  of  the  race. 

After  due  consideration  of  these  plans  the  Committee  reached  the  conclusion 
that  the  ends  aimed  at  in  the  second  and  third  plans  could  be  attained  by  taking 
the  first  plan  as  a  basis,  and  including  in  its  subdivisions,  so  far  as  was  deemed 
advisable,  the  subjects  proposed  in  the  second  and  third  plans.  They  accordingly 
adopted  a  resolution  that  "Mr.  Miinsterberg's  plan  be  adopted  as  setting  forth 


THE  HISTORY  OF   THE  CONGRESS  9 

the  general  object  of  the  Congress  and  definmg  the  scope  of  its  work,  and  that 
Mr.  Small's  plan  be  communicated  to  the  General  Committee  as  containing  sug- 
gestions as  to  details,  but  without  recommending  its  adoption  as  a  whole." 

DATE    OF   THE    CONGRESS 

Your  Committee  is  of  opinion  that,  in  view  of  the  climatic  conditions  at  St.  Louis 
during  the  summer  and  early  autimm,  it  is  desirable  that  the  meeting  of  this 
general  Congress  be  held  during  the  six  days  beginning  on  Monday,  September  19, 
1904,  and  continuing  until  the  Saturday  following.  Special  associations  choosing 
St.  Louis  as  their  meeting-place  may  then  convene  at  such  other  dates  as  may  be 
deemed  fit;  but  it  is  suggested  that  learned  societies  whose  field  is  connected  with 
that  of  the  Congress  should  meet  during  the  week  beginning  September  26! 

The  sectional  discussions  of  the  Congress  will  then  be  continued  by  these 
societies,  the  whole  forming  a  continuous  discussion  of  human  progress  during 
the  last  century. 

PLAN    OF   ADDRESSES 

The  Committee  believe  that  in  order  to  carry  out  the  proposed  plan  in  the  most 
effective  way  it  is  necessary  that  the  addresses  be  prepared  by  the  highest  living 
authorities  in  each  and  every  branch.  In  the  last  subdivisions,  each  section 
embraces  two  papers;  one  on  the  history  of  the  subject  during  the  last  one  hun- 
dred years  and  the  other  on  the  problems  of  to-day. 

The  programme  of  papers  suggested  by  the  Committee  as  embraced  in  Pro- 
fessor Miinsterberg's  plan  may  be  summarized  as  foUows :  — 

On  the  first  day  four  papers  wiU  be  read  on  the  general  subject,  and  four  on 
each  of  the  four  large  divisions,  twenty  in  all.  On  the  second  day  those  four  divi- 
sions wiU  be  divided  into  twenty  groups,  or  departments,  each  of  which  will  have 
four  papers  referring  to  the  divisions  and  relations  of  the  sciences,  eighty  in  all. 
On  the  last  four  days,  two  papers  in  each  of  the  120  sections,  240  in  aU,  thus 
making  a  total  of  340  papers. 

In  view  of  the  fact  that  the  men  who  wiU  make  the  addresses  should  not  be 
expected  to  bear  all  the  expense  of  their  attendance  at  the  Congress,  it  seems 
advisable  that  the  authorities  of  the  Fair  should  provide  for  the  expenses  neces- 
sarily incurred  in  the  journey,  as  weU  as  pay  a  small  honorarium  for  the  addresses. 
The  Committee  suggest,  therefore,  that  each  American  invited  be  offered  $100  for 
his  traveling  expenses  and  each  European  $400.  In  addition  to  this  that  each 
receive  $150  as  an  honorarium.  Assuming  that  one  half  of  those  invited  to  deliver 
addresses  wiU  be  Americans  and  one  half  Europeans,  this  arrangement  wiU  involve 
the  expenditure  of  $136,000.  This  estimate  will  be  reduced  if  the  same  person 
prepares  more  than  one  address.  It  wiU  also  be  reduced  if  more  than  half  of  the 
speakers  are  Americans,  and  increased  in  the  opposite  case. 

As  the  Committee  is  not  advised  of  the  amount  which  the  management  of  the 
Exposition  may  appropriate  for  the  purpose  of  the  Congress,  it  cannot,  at  present, 
enter  further  into  details  of  adjustment,  but  it  records  its  opinion  that  the  sum 
suggested  is  the  least  by  which  the  ends  sought  to  be  attained  by  the  Congress  can 
be  accomplished.  To  this  must  be  added  the  expenses  of  administration  and 
publication. 

All  addresses  paid  for  by  the  Congress  should  be  regarded  as  its  property,  and 
be  printed  and  published  together,  thus  constituting  a  comprehensive  work 
exhibiting  the  unity,  progress,  and  present  state  of  knowledge. 

This  plan  does  not  preclude  the  delivery  of  more  than  one  address  by  a  single 
scholar.  The  directors  of  the  Exposition  may  sometimes  find  it  advisable  to  ask 
the  same  scholar  to  deliver  two  addresses,  possibly  even  three. 


10  THE   HISTORY   OF  THE   CONGRESS 

The  Committee  recommends  that  full  liberty  be  allowed  to  each  section  of  the 
Congress  in  arranging  the  general  character  and  programme  of  its  discussions 
within  the  field  proposed. 

As  an  example  of  how  the  plan  will  work  m  the  case  of  any  one  section,  the 
Committee  take  the  case  of  a  neurologist  desiring  to  profit  by  those  discussions 
which  relate  to  his  branch  of  medicine.  This  falls  under  C  of  the  four  main 
divisions  as  related  to  the  physical  sciences.  His  interest  on  the  first  day  will 
therefore  be  centred  in  Division  C,  wliere  he  may  hear  the  general  discussion  of 
the  physical  sciences  and  the  relations  to  the  other  sciences.  On  the  second  day 
he  wiU  hear  four  papers  in  Group  IS  on  the  subjects  embraced  in  the  general 
science  of  antliropology ;  one  on  its  fundamental  conceptions;  one  on  its 
methods  and  two  on  the  relation  of  anthropology  to  the  sciences  most  closely  con- 
nected with  it.  During  the  remaining  four  days  he  will  meet  with  the  represent- 
atives of  medicine  and  its  related  subjects,  who  will  divide  into  sections,  and 
listen  to  four  papers  in  each  section.  One  paper  wiU  consider  the  progress  of 
that  section  in  the  last  one  hundred  years,  one  paper  will  be  devoted  to  the 
problems  of  to-day,  lea\'ing  room  for  such  contributions  and  discussions  as  may 
seem  appropriate  during  the  remainder  of  the  day. 

COOPERATION    OF   LEARNED    SOCIETIES   INVOKED 

In  presenting  this  general  plan,  your  Committee  wishes  to  point  out  the  diffi- 
culty of  deciding  in  advance  what  subjects  should  be  included  in  every  section. 
Therefore,  the  Committee  deems  it  of  the  utinost  importance  to  secure  the  advice 
and  assistance  of  learned  societies  in  this  country  in  perfecting  the  details  of  the 
proposed  plan,  especially  the  selection  of  speakers  and  the  programme  of  work  in 
each  section.  It  will  facilitate  the  latter  purpose  if  such  societies  be  invited  and 
encouraged  to  hold  meetings  at  St.  Louis  during  the  week  immediately  preceding, 
or,  preferably,  the  week  following  the  General  Congress.  The  selection  of  speakers 
should  be  made  as  soon  as  possible,  and,  in  any  case,  before  the  end  of  the  present 
academic  year,  in  order  that  formal  invitations  may  be  issued  and  final  arrange- 
ments made  with  the  speakers  a  year  in  advance  of  the  Congress. 

CONCLUDING   SUGGESTIONS 

With  the  view  of  securing  the  cooperation  of  the  governments  and  leading 
scholars  of  the  principal  countries  of  Western  and  Central  Europe  in  the  proposed 
Congress,  it  seems  advisable  to  send  two  commissioners  to  these  countries  for  this 
purpose.  It  seems  unnecessary  to  extend  the  operations  of  this  commission  out- 
side the  European  continent  or  to  other  than  the  leading  countries.  In  other 
cases  arrangements  can  be  made  by  correspondence. 

It  is  the  opinion  of  the  Committee  that  an  American  of  world-wide  reputation 
as  a  scholar  should  be  selected  to  preside  over  the  Congress. 
AH  which  is  respectfully  submitted. 

(Signed)  Simon  Newcomb, 

Chairman ; 
George  F.  Moore, 
John  B.  Moore, 
Hugo  Munsterberg, 
Albion  W.  Small, 
William  H.  Welch, 
Elihu  Thomson, 

Committee. 


THE   HISTORY   OF   THE   CONGRESS  11 

The  Administrative  Board  met  on  January  19  to  receive  the  report 
of  the  Committee  on  Plan  and  Scope  which  was  presented  by  Dr. 
Newcomb.  Professor  Miinsterberg  and  Professor  John  Bassett  Moore 
were  also  present  by  invitation  to  discuss  the  details  of  the  scheme. 
In  the  afternoon  the  Board  went  into  executive  session,  and  the 
following  recommendations  were  adopted  and  transmitted  by  the 
Director  of  Congresses  to  the  Committee  on  Congresses  of  the  Expo- 
sition and  to  the  President  and  Executive  Committee,  who  duly 
approved  them. 

To  the  Director  of  Congresses :  — 

The  Administrative  Board  have  the  honor  to  make  the  following  recommenda- 
tions in  reference  to  the  Department  of  Congresses :  — 

(1)  That  there  be  held  in  coimection  with  the  Universal  Exposition  of  St.  Louis 
in  1904,  an  International  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science. 

(2)  That  the  plan  recommended  by  the  Committee  on  Plan  and  Scope  for  a 
general  congress  of  Arts  and  Science,  to  be  held  during  the  six  days  beginning  on 
Monday,  September  19,  1904,  be  approved  and  adopted,  subject  to  such  revision 
in  point  of  detail  as  may  be  advisable,  preserving  its  fundamental  principles. 

(3)  That  Simon  Newcomb,  LL.D.,  of  Washington,  D.  C,  be  named  for  President 
of  the  International  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science,  provided  for  in  the  foregoing 
resolution. 

(4)  That  Professor  Miinsterberg,  of  Harvard  University,  and  Professor  Albion 
W.  Small,  of  the  University  of  Chicago,  be  invited  to  act  as  Vice-Presidents  of 
the  Congress. 

(5)  That  the  Directors  of  the  World's  Fair  be  requested  to  change  the  name  of 
this  Board  from  the  "Advisory  Board"  to  the  "Administrative  Board  of  the 
International  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science." 

(6)  That  the  detailed  arrangements  for  the  Congress  be  intrusted  to  a  com- 
mittee consisting  of  the  President  and  two  Vice-Presidents  already  named,  sub- 
ject to  the  general  oversight  and  control  of  the  Administrative  Board,  and  that 
the  Directors  of  the  Exposition  be  requested  to  make  appropriate  provision  for 
their  compensation  and  necessary  expenses. 

(7)  That  it  be  recommended  to  the  Directors  of  the  World's  Fair  that  appro- 
priate provision  should  be  made  in  the  office  of  the  Department  of  Congresses  for 
an  executive  secretary  and  such  clerical  assistance  as  may  be  needed. 

(8)  That  the  following  payment  be  recommended  to  those  scholars  who  accept 
invitations  to  participate  and  do  a  specified  piece  of  work,  or  submit  a  specified 
contribution  in  the  International  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science:  For  traveling 
expenses  for  a  European  scholar,  $500.  For  traveling  expenses  for  an  American 
scholar,  $150. 

(9)  That  provision  be  made  for  the  publication  of  the  proceedings  of  the  Con- 
gress in  suitable  form  to  constitute  a  permanent  memorial  of  the  work  of  the 
World's  Fair  for  the  promotion  of  science  and  art,  under  competent  editorial 
supervision. 

(10)  That  an  appropriation  of  $200,000  be  made  to  cover  expenses  of  the 
Department  of  Congresses,  of  which  sum  $130,000  be  specifically  appropriated  for 
an  International  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science,  and  the  remainder  to  cover  aU 
expenses  connected  with  the  publication  of  the  proceedings  of  said  Interna- 
tional Congress  of  Arts  and  Science,  and  the  expenses  for  promotion  of  aU  other 
congresses. 


12  THE  HISTORY  OF   THE  CONGRESS 

In  addition  to  the  foregoing  recommendations,  Professor  Miinster- 
berg  was  requested  at  his  eariiest  convenience  to  furnish  each  member 
with  a  revised  plan  of  his  classification,  which  would  reduce  as  far  as 
possible  the  number  of  sections  into  which  the  Congress  was  finally 
to  be  divided. 

With  the  adjournment  of  the  Board  on  January  19  the  Congress 
may  be  fairly  said  to  have  been  launched  upon  its  definite  course, 
and  such  changes  as  were  thereafter  made  in  the  programme  did  not 
in  any  wise  affect  the  principle  upon  which  the  Congress  was  based, 
but  were  due  to  the  demands  of  time,  of  expediency,  and  in  some 
cases  to  the  accidents  attending  the  participation.  The  organization 
of  the  Congress  and  the  personnel  of  its  officers  from  this  time  on 
remained  unchanged,  and  the  history  of  the  meeting  is  one  of  steady 
and  progressive  development.  The  Committee  on  Plan  and  Scope 
were  discharged  of  their  duties,  with  a  vote  of  thanks  for  the 
laborious  and  painstaking  work  which  they  had  accomplished  and 
the  thoroughly  scientific  and  novel  plan  for  an  international  congress 
which  they  had  recommended. 

It  was  determined  by  the  Administrative  Board  to  keep  the  serv- 
ices of  three  of  the  members  of  the  Committee  on  Plan  and  Scope, 
who  should  act  as  a  scientific  organizing  committee  and  who  should 
also  be  the  presiding  officers  of  the  Congress.  The  choice  for  President 
of  the  Congress  fell  without  debate  to  the  dean  of  American  scientific 
circles,  whose  eminent  services  to  the  Government  of  the  United 
States  and  whose  recognized  position  in  foreign  and  domestic  sci- 
entific circles  made  him  particularly  fitted  to  preside  over  such  an 
international  gathering  of  the  leading  scientists  of  the  world.  Dr. 
Simon  Newcomb,  retired  Professor  of  Mathematics,  United  States 
Navy.  Professor  Hugo  Miinsterberg,  of  Harvard  University,  and  Pro- 
fessor Albion  W.  Small,  of  the  University  of  Chicago,  were  designated 
as  the  first  and  second  Vice-Presidents  respectively. 

The  work  of  the  succeeding  spring,  with  both  the  Organizing  Com- 
mittee and  the  Administrative  Board,  was  devoted  to  the  perfecting 
of  the  programme  and  the  selection  of  foreign  scientists  to  be  invited 
to  participate  in  the  Congress.  The  theory  of  the  development  of 
the  programme  and  its  logical  bases  are  fully  and  forcibly  treated  by 
Professor  Miinsterberg  in  the  succeeding  chapter,  and  therefore  will 
not  be  touched  upon  in  this  record  of  facts.  As  an  illustration  of  the 
growth  of  the  programme,  however,  it  is  interesting  to  compare  its 
form,  which  was  adopted  at  the  next  meeting  of  the  Organizing 
Committee  on  February  23,  1903,  in  New  York  City,  with  its  final 
form  as  given  in  the  completed  programme  presented  at  St.  Louis 
in  September,  1904  (pp.  47-49).  No  better  illustration  can  be  given 
of  the  immense  amount  of  labor  and  painstaking  adjustment,  both 
to  scientific  and  to  physical  conditions,  and  of  the  admirable  adapt- 


THE   HISTORY  OF   THE   CONGRESS 


13 


ability  of  the  original  plan  to  the  exigencies  of  actual  practice.  At 
the  meeting  of  February  23,  1903,  which  was  attended  by  all  of  the 
members  of  the  Organizing  Committee  and  by  President  Butler  of 
the  Administrative  Board,  it  was  determined  that  the  number  of 
Departments  should  be  sixteen,  with  the  following  designations:  — 

A.   NORMATIVE   SCIENCES 

1.  Philosophical  Sciences.  2.  Mathematical  Sciences. 


B.   HISTORICAL 


3.  Political  Sciences. 

4.  Legal  Sciences. 

5.  Economic  Sciences. 

6.  Philological  Sciences. 


SCIENCES 

7.  Pedagogical  Sciences. 

8.  ^Esthetic  Sciences. 

9.  Theological  Sciences. 


C.   PHYSICAL   SCIENCES 


10.  General  Physical  Sciences. 

11.  Astronomical  Sciences. 

12.  Geological  Sciences. 


13.  Biological  Sciences. 

14.  Anthropological  Sciences. 


D.   MENTAL   SCIENCES 
15.  Psychological  Sciences.  16.  Sociological  Sciences. 


Indo-Iranian  Languages. 
Semitic  Languages. 
Classical  Languages. 
Modem  Languages. 
History  of  Education. 
Educational  Institutions. 
History  of  Architecture. 
History  of  Fine  Arts. 
History  of  Music. 
Oriental  Literature. 
Classical  Literature. 
Modem  Literature. 
Architecture. 
Fine  Arts. 
Music. 

Primitive  Religions. 
Asiatic  Religions. 
Semitic  Rehgions. 
Christianity. 
Religious  Institutions. 
Mechanics  and  Soimd. 
Light  and  Heat. 
Electricity. 
Inorganic  Chemistry. 
Organic  Chemistry. 
Physical  Chemistry. 
Mechanical  Technology. 
Optical  Technology. 
Electrical  Technology. 


SECTIONS 

1, 

,  a  Metaphysics. 

6.  a 

b  Logic. 

b 

c  Ethics. 

c 

d  .Esthetics. 

d 

2, 

,  a  Algebra. 

7.  a 

b  Geometry. 

aa 

c  Statistical  Methods. 

8.  a 

3 

.  a  Classical  Political  History  of 

b 

Asia. 

c 

b  Classical  PoUtical  History  of 

d 

Europe. 

e 

c  Medieval  Political  History    of 

f 

Europe. 

aa 

d  Modem   Pohtical    History    of 

bb 

Europe. 

cc 

e  Pohtical  History  of  America. 

9.  a 

4 

.  a  History  of  Roman  Law. 

b 

b  History  of  Common  Law. 

c 

aa  Constitutional  Law. 

d 

bb  Criminal  Law. 

aa 

cc  Civil  Law. 

10.  a 

dd  History  of  International  Law. 

b 

5 

.  a  History  of  Economic  Institu- 

c 

tions. 

d 

6  History  of  Econopaic  Theories. 

e 

c  Economic  Law. 

f 

aa  Finance. 

aa 

bb  Commerce  and  Transportation. 

bb 

cc  Labor. 

cc 

14 


THE  HISTORY  OF   THE  CONGRESS 


SECTIONS  —  continued 


10.  dd  Chemical  Teclinology. 

11.  a  Theoretical  Astronomy. 
b  Astrophysics. 

12.  a  Geodesy. 
b  Geology. 

c  Mineralogy. 

d  Physiography. 

e  Meteorology. 
aa  Surveying. 
bb  Metallurgy. 

13.  a  Botany. 

b  Plant  Physiology. 

c  Ecology. 

d  Bacteriology. 

e  Zoology. 

/  Embryology. 

g  Comparative  Anatomy. 

h  Ph5rsiology. 
aa  Agronomy. 
bb  Veterinary  Medicine. 

14.  Anthropological  Sciences: 
a  Human  Anatomy. 

b  Human  Physiology. 
c  Neurology. 


d  Physical  Chemistry. 

e  Pathology. 

/  Raceomatology. 
aa  Hygiene. 
bb  Contagious  Diseases. 

cc  Internal  Medicine. 
dd  Surgery. 
ee  Gynecology. 
//  Ophthalmology. 
gg  Therapeutics. 
hh  Dentistry. 

15.  Psychological  Sciences: 
a  General  Psychology. 

b  Experimental  Psychology. 
c  Comparative  Psychology. 
d  Child  Psychology. 
e  Abnormal  Psychology. 

16.  Sociological  Sciences: 
a  Social  Morphology. 

b  Social  Psychology. 
c  Laws  of  Civilization. 
d  Laws  of  Language  and  Myths. 
e  Etlmology. 
aa  Social  Technology. 


It  was  also  resolved,  that  the  discussion  of  subjects  falling  under 
the  first  four  divisions  should  be  held  in  the  forenoon  of  each  of  the 
four  days,  from  Wednesday  until  Saturday,  and  those  relating  to 
the  three  divisions  of  Practical  Science  in  the  afternoon  of  the  same 
days.  The  programme  was  thus  rearranged  by  the  addition  of  the 
following :  — 

E.   UTILITARIAN   SCIENCES 


17.  Medical  Sciences: 
a  Hygiene. 

b  Sanitation. 

c  Contagious  Diseases. 

d  Internal  Medicine. 

e  Psychiatry. 

/  Surgery. 

g  Gynecology. 

h  Ophthalmology. 

i  Otology. 

J  Therapeutics. 

k  Dentistry. 

18.  Practical  Economic  Sciences: 

a  Extractive      Productions      of 
Wealth. 


b  Transportation, 
c  Commerce. 
d  Postal  Service. 
e  Money  and  Banking. 
19.       Technological  Sciences: 
a  Mechanical  Technology. 
b  Electrical  Technology. 
c  Chemical  Technology. 
d  Optical  Technology. 
e  Surveying. 
/  Metallurgy. 
g  Agronomy. 
h  Veterinarv  Medicine. 


THE  HISTORY   OF   THE  CONGRESS  15 

F.    REGULATIVE    SCIENCES 

20.  Practical  Political  Sciences :  c  Criminal  Law. 
a  Internal  Practical  Politics.                       d  Civil  Law. 

&  National  Practical  Politics.  22.  Practical  Social  Sciences: 

c  Tariff.  a  Treatment  of  the  Poor. 

d  Taxation.  h  Treatment  of  the  Defective, 

e  Municipal  Practical  Politics.  c  Treatment  of  the  Dependent. 

/  Colonial  Practical  Politics.  d  Treatment  of  Vice  and  Crime. 

21.  Practical  Legal  Sciences:  e  Problems  of  Labor. 

a  International  Law.  /  Problems  of  the  Family. 

6  Constitutional  Law. 

G.    CULTURAL    SCIENCES 

23.       Practical  Educational  Sciences :  /Publications. 

a  Kindergarten  and  Home.  24.       Practical  ^Esthetic  Sciences: 
h  Primary  Education.  a  Architecture, 

c  Universities  and    Research  —  h  Fine  Arts. 

Secondary.  c  Music. 

d  Moral  Education.  d  Landscape  Architecture. 

e  Esthetic  Education.  25.       Practical  Religious  Sciences: 
/  Manual  Training.  a  Religious  Education. 

g  University.  h  Training  for  Religious  Ser\'ice. 

h  Libraries.  c  Missions. 

i  Museums.  d  Religious  Influence. 

The  programme  was  again  thoroughly  revised  at  the  meeting  of  the 
Organizing  Committee  on  April  9,  1903,  at  Hotel  Manhattan,  and  as 
thus  amended  was  submitted  to  the  Administrative  Board  at  a  meet- 
ing held  in  New  York  on  April  11.  A  careful  consideration  of  the 
programme  at  this  meeting,  and  a  final  revision  made  at  the  meeting 
of  the  Administrative  Board  at  the  St.  Louis  Club  April  30,  1903, 
brought  it  practically  into  its  final  shape,  with  such  minor  changes 
as  were  found  necessary  in  the  latter  days  of  the  Congress  due  to  the 
unexpected  declinations  of  foreign  speakers  at  the  last  moment.  The 
continuous  and  exacting  work  done  in  perfecting  the  programme  by 
each  member  of  the  Organizing  Committee  and  by  the  Chairman  of 
the  Administrative  Board  deserves  special  mention,  and  was  pro- 
ductive of  the  best  results  by  its  logical  appeal  to  the  scientific  world. 
The  programme  as  finally  worked  out  in  orderly  detail,  shortened  in 
many  departments  by  various  exigencies,  may  be  found  on  pages  47 
to  49  of  this  volume. 

PARTICIPATION   AND    SUPPORT 

The  general  plan  of  the  Congress  having  been  determined  and  the 
prcgramme  practically  perfected  by  M&y  1,  1903,  two  most  import- 
ant questions  demanded  the  attention  of  the  Administrative  Board: 
first,  the  participation  in  the  Congress,  both  foreign  and  domestic; 


16  THE  HISTORY   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

second,  the  support  of  the  scientific  pubUc.  At  a  meeting  of  the  Board 
held  in  New  York  City  April  11,  1903,  these  points  were  given  full 
consideration.  It  was  determined  that  the  list  of  speakers  both  for- 
eign and  domestic  should  be  made  up  on  the  advice  of  men  of  letters 
and  of  scientific  thought  in  this  country,  and  accordingly  there  was 
sent  to  the  officers  of  the  various  scientific  societies  in  the  United 
States,  to  heads  of  university  departments  and  to  every  prominent 
exponent  of  science  and  art  in  this  country,  a  printed  announcement 
and  tentative  programme  of  the  Congress,  and  a  letter  asking  advice 
as  to  the  scientists  best  fitted  in  view  of  the  object  of  the  Congress 
to  prepare  an  address.  From  the  hundreds  of  replies  received  in 
response  to  this  appeal  were  made  up  the  original  lists  of  invited 
speakers,  and  only  those  were  placed  thereon  who  were  the  choice  of 
a  fair  majority  of  the  representatives  of  the  particular  science  under 
selection.  The  Administrative  Board  reserved  to  itself  the  full  right 
to  reject  any  of  these  names  or  to  change  them  so  as  to  promote  the 
best  interests  of  the  Congress,  but  in  nearly  every  instance  it  would 
be  safe  to  say  that  the  person  selected  was  highly  satisfactory  to  the 
great  majority  of  his  fellow  scientists  in  this  country.  Many  changes 
were  unavoidably  made  at  the  last  moment  to  meet  the  situation 
caused  by  withdrawals  and  declinations,  but  the  list  of  second  choices 
was  so  complete,  and  in  many  cases  there  was  such  a  delicate  balance 
between  the  first  and  second  choice,  that  there  was  no  difficulty 
in  keeping  the  standard  of  the  programme  to  its  original  high 
plane. 

It  was  early  determined  that  the  seven  Division  speakers  and  the 
forty-eight  Department  speakers,  which  occupied  the  first  two  days 
of  the  programme,  should  be  Americans,  and  that  these  Division  and 
Department  addresses  should  be  a  contribution  of  American  scholar- 
ship to  the  general  scientific  thought  of  the  world.  This  decision 
commended  itself  to  the  scientific  public  both  at  home  and  abroad, 
and  it  was  so  carried  out.  It  was  further  determined  that  the  Division 
and  Department  speakers  and  the  foreign  speakers  should  be  selected 
during  the  summer  of  1903,  and  that  the  American  participation  in 
the  Section  addresses  should  be  determined  after  it  was  definitely 
known  what  the  foreign  participation  would  be.  In  view  of  the 
importance  of  the  Congress,  it  was  deemed  inadvisable  to  attempt 
to  interest  foreign  scientific  circles  by  correspondence,  and  it  was 
further  decided  to  pay  a  special  compliment  to  each  invited  speaker 
by  sending  an  invitation  at  the  hands  of  special  delegates.  Arrange- 
ments were  therefore  made  for  Dr.  Newcomb  and  Professors  Miinster- 
berg  and  Small  to  proceed  to  Europe  during  the  summer  of  1903,  and 
to  present  in  person  to  the  scientific  circles  of  Europe  and  to  the 
scientists  specially  desired  to  deliver  addresses  the  complete  plan 
and  scope  of  the  Congress  and  an  invitation  to  participate. 


THE  HISTORY   OF   THE   CONGRESS  17 

INVITATIONS   TO    FOREIGN    SPEAKERS 

The  members  of  the  Organizing  Committee,  armed  with  very  strong 
credentials  from  the  State  Department  to  the  diplomatic  service 
abroad,  sailed  in  the  early  summer  of  1903  to  present  the  invitation  of 
the  Exposition  to  the  selected  scientists.  Dr.  Newcomb  sailed  May  6, 
Professor  Miinsterberg  May  30,  and  Professor  Small  June  6.  A  general 
interest  in  the  project  had  at  this  time  become  aroused,  and  there 
was  assured  a  respectful  hearing.  Both  the  President  of  the  United 
States  and  the  Emperor  of  Germany  expressed  their  warm  interest 
in  the  plan,  and  the  State  Department  at  Washington  gave  to  the 
Congress  both  on  this  occasion  and  on  succeeding  occasions  its  effect- 
ive aid.  The  Director  of  Congresses  wishes  to  express  his  obligations 
both  to  the  late  Secretary  Hay  and  to  Assistant-Secretary  Loomis  for 
their  valuable  suggestions  and  courteous  cooperation  in  all  matters 
relating  to  the  foreign  participation.  Strong  support  was  also  given 
the  Committee  and  the  plan  of  the  Congress  by  Commissioner-General 
Lewald  of  Germany,  and  Commissioner-General  Lagrave  of  France. 
Throughout  the  entire  Congress  period,  both  of  these  energetic  Com- 
missioners-General placed  themselves  actively  at  the  disposition  of 
the  Department  in  promoting  the  attendance  of  scientists  from  their 
respective  countries. 

Geographically  the  division  between  the  three  members  of  the 
Organizing  Committee  gave  to  Dr.  Newcomb,  France;  to  Professor 
Miinsterberg,  Germany,  Austria,  and  Switzerland;  and  to  Professor 
Small,  England,  Russia,  Italy,  and  a  part  of  Austria.  It  was  also 
agreed  that  Dr.  Newcomb  should  have  special  oversight  of  the 
departments  of  Mathematics,  Physics,  Astronomy,  Biology,  and 
Technology;  Professor  Miinsterberg,  special  charge  of  Philosophy, 
Philology,  Art,  Education,  Psychology,  and  Medicine;  and  that 
Professor  Small  should  look  after  Politics,  Law,  Economics,  Theology, 
Sociology,  and  Religion.  The  Committee  worked  independently  of 
each  other,  but  met  once  during  the  summer  at  Munich  to  compare 
results  and  to  determine  their  closing  movements. 

The  public  and  even  the  Exposition  authorities  have  probably 
never  realized  the  delicacy  and  the  extremely  careful  adjustment 
exercised  by  the  Organizing  Committee  in  their  summer's  campaign. 
Scientists  are  as  a  class  sensitive,  jealous  of  their  reputations,  and 
loath  to  undertake  long  journeys  to  a  distant  country  for  congress 
purposes.  The  amount  of  labor  devolving  upon  the  Committee  to 
find  the  scientists  scattered  over  all  Europe;  the  careful  and  pains- 
taking presentation  to  each  of  the  plan  of  the  Congress;  the  appeal 
to  their  scientific  pride;  the  hearing  of  a  thousand  objections,  and 
the  answering  of  each;  the  disappointments  incurred;  the  substi- 
tutions made  necessary  at  the  last  moment;  —  all  sum  up  a  task  of 


18  THE  HISTORY   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

the  greatest  difficulty  and  of  enormous  labor.  The  remarkable  success 
with  which  the  mission  was  crowned  stands  out  the  more  promi- 
nently in  view  of  these  conditions.  When  the  Committee  returned  in 
the  latter  part  of  September,  they  had  visited  every  important  coun- 
try of  Europe,  delivered  more  than  one  hundred  fifty  personal  invita- 
tions, and  for  the  one  hundred  twenty-eight  sections  had  secured  one 
hundred  seventeen  acceptances. 

At  a  meeting  of  the  Administrative  Board,  which  met  with  the 
Organizing  Committee  on  October  13,  1903,  a  full  report  of  the 
European  trip  was  received  and  ways  and  means  considered  for  insur- 
ing the  attendance  from  abroad.  A  list  of  the  foreign  acceptances  was 
ordered  printed  at  once  for  general  distribution,  and  the  Chairman  of 
the  Administrative  Board  was  requested  to  address  a  letter  to  each 
of  the  foreign  scientists  confirming  the  action  of  the  special  delegates 
and  giving  additional  information  as  to  the  length  of  addresses,  and 
rules  and  details  governing  the  administration  of  the  Congress. 

DEATH    OF    FREDERICK    W.    HOLLS 

The. number  of  the  Administrative  Board  was  decreased  during 
the  summer  by  the  sudden  death  of  the  Hon.  Frederick  W.  HoUs,  on 
July  23,  1903.  Mr.  Holls  had  been  intensely  interested  in  the  develop- 
ment of  the  Congress  from  its  earliest  days,  and  was  very  instru- 
mental in  determining  the  form  in  which  it  was  finally  promoted. 
His  great  influence  abroad  as  a  member  of  the  Hague  Conference, 
and  his  high  standing  in  legal  and  literary  circles  in  this  country, 
rendered  him  one  of  the  most  prominent  members  of  the  Board.  A 
resolution  of  regret  at  his  untimely  death  was  spread  upon  the  min- 
utes of  the  Administrative  Board  at  the  meeting  in  October,  and  it 
was  decided  that  his  place  upon  the  Board  should  remain  unfilled. 

DOMESTIC    PARTICIPATION 

At  this  same  meeting  of  October  13,  active  measures  were  taken  to 
forward  the  American  participation  in  the  Congress.  The  necessity 
was  now  very  evident  that  our  strongest  men  of  science  must  be 
induced  to  take  part,  in  order  to  compare  favorably  with  the  leading 
minds  which  Europe  was  sending.  The  Organizing  Committee  were 
instructed  to  consult  the  American  scientific  societies  and  associations 
regarding  the  selection  of  American  speakers,  and  also  in  reference 
to  presiding  officials  for  each  section.  Six  weeks  was  considered  suf- 
ficient for  this  task,  and  the  Committee  were  asked  to  submit  to  the 
Administrative  Board  at  a  meeting  in  New  York,  on  December  3 
and  4,  their  recommendations  for  American  speakers. 

An  immense  amount  of  detailed  labor,  in  the  way  of  correspond- 
ence, now  devolved  upon  the  Organizing  Committee  as  well  as  upon 
the  Director  of  Congresses,  and  a  branch  office  was  established  in 


THE  HISTORY   OF   THE  CONGRESS  19 

Washington  equipped  with  clerks  and  stenographers  under  the  charge 
of  Dr.  Newcomb,  who  devoted  the  greater  portion  of  his  time  for  the 
next  six  months  to  the  many  details  connected  with  the  selection 
of  foreign  and  American  speakers  and  chairmen.  The  meeting  of  the 
Administrative  Board  in  New  York  in  December,  and  a  similar 
meeting  with  the  Organizing  Committee  held  at  the  St.  Louis  Club  on 
December  28,  were  given  over  entirely  to  perfecting  the  personnel  of 
the  programme.  Great  care  was  exerted  in  selecting  the  chairmen 
of  the  departments  and  sections,  inasmuch  as  they  must  be  men  of 
international  reputation  and  conceded  strength.  For  the  secretary- 
ships younger  men  of  promise  and  ability  were  selected,  chiefly  from 
university  circles.  Both  the  chairmen  and  secretaries  served  without 
compensation. 

The  work  of  the  late  winter  was  a  continuance  of  the  perfecting  of 
details,  and  at  a  meeting  of  the  Administrative  Board  held  in  New 
York  in  February,  1904,  a  final  approval  was  given  to  the  programme 
and  the  speakers.  The  imminent  approach  of  the  Exposition  and  the 
work  of  the  college  commencement  season  made  it  impossible  for 
further  general  meetings,  and  on  June  1  the  Organizing  Committee 
was  constituted  a  committee  with  power  to  fill  vacancies  in  the  pro- 
gramme or  to  amend  the  programme  as  circumstances  might  demand. 
All  suggestions  with  reference  to  details  were  to  be  made  directly  to 
the  Director  of  Congresses,  upon  whom  devolved  from  this  time  for- 
ward the  entire  executive  control  of  the  Congress. 

ASSEMBLY   HALLS 

The  highly  diversified  nature  of  the  Congress  and  the  holding  of 
one  hundred  twenty-eight  section  meetings  in  four  days'  time  ren- 
dered necessary  a  large  number  of  meeting-places  centrally  located. 
The  Exposition  was  fortunate  in  having  the  use  of  the  new  plant  of 
the  Washington  University,  nine  large  buildings  of  which  had  been 
erected.  Many  of  these  buildings  contained  lecture  halls  and  assembly 
rooms,  seating  from  one  hundred  fifty  to  fifteen  hundred  people. 
Sixteen  halls  were  necessary  to  accommodate  the  full  number  of 
sections  running  at  any  one  time,  and  of  this  number  twelve  were 
available  in  the  group  of  University  Buildings;  the  other  four  were 
found  in  the  lecture  halls  of  the  Education  Building,  Mines  and 
Metallurgy  Building,  Agriculture  Building,  and  the  Transportation 
Building.  The  opening  exercises,  at  which  the  entire  Congress  was 
assembled,  was  held  in  Festival  Hall,  capable  of  seating  three 
thousand  people.  In  the  assignment  of  halls  care  was  taken  so  far  as 
possible  to  assign  the  larger  halls  to  the  more  popular  subjects,  but  it 
often  happened  that  a  great  speaker  was  of  necessity  assigned  to 
a  smaller  hall.  Two  of  the  halls  also  proved  bad  for  speaking  owing 
to  the  traffic  of  the  Intramural  Railway,  and  there  was  lacking  in 


20  THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

nearly  all  of  the  halls  that  academic  peace  and  quiet  which  usually 
surrounds  gatherings  of  a  scientific  nature.  This,  however,  was  to  be 
expected  in  an  exposition  atmosphere,  and  was  readily  acquiesced 
in  by  the  speakers  themselves,  and  very  little  objection  was  heard  to 
the  halls  as  assigned.  Every  one  seemed  to  recognize  the  fact  that  the 
immediate  value  of  the  meeting  lay  in  the  commingling  and  fellowship, 
and  that  the  addresses,  of  which  one  could  hear  at  most  only  one  in  six- 
teen, could  not  be  judged  in  the  proper  light  until  their  publication. 

SUPPORT    OF   THE   SCIENTIFIC    PUBLIC 

A  strong  effort  was  made  by  the  Organizing  Committee  to  secure 
the  attendance  of  an  audience  which  should  not  only  in  its  proportions 
be  complimentary  to  the  eminence  of  the  speakers,  but  also  be  thor- 
oughly appreciative  of  the  addresses  and  conversant  with  the  topic 
under  discussion.  Letters  were  therefore  sent  to  all  of  the  prominent 
scientific  societies  in  the  United  States,  asking  that  wherever  possible 
the  meetings  of  the  society  be  set  for  the  Congress  week  in  St.  Louis, 
and  wherever  this  was  not  possible  that  the  societies  send  special 
delegates  to  attend  the  Congress,  and  urge  their  membership  to  make 
an  effort  to  be  present.  Personal  letters  were  also  sent  to  the  leading 
members  of  the  different  professions  and  sciences,  to  the  faculties  of 
universities  and  colleges,  urging  them  to  attend,  and  pointing  out  the 
necessity  of  the  support  of  the  American  scientific  public. 

Special  invitations  were  also  sent  in  the  name  of  the  Organizing 
Committee  to  the  leading  authorities  of  the  various  subjects  under 
discussion  in  the  Congress,  asking  them  to  contribute  a  ten-minute 
paper  to  any  section  in  which  they  were  particularly  interested.  The 
result  of  this  careful  campaign,  in  addition  to  the  general  exploita- 
tion which  the  Congress  received,  was  such  a  flattering  attendance  of 
American  scientists,  as  to  be  both  a  compliment  to  the  European 
speakers  and  a  benefit  to  scientific  thought.  Many  societies,  such  as 
the  American  Neurological  Association,  American  Philological  Asso- 
ciation, American  Mathematical  Society,  Physical  and  Chemical 
Societies  of  America,  American  Astronomical  Society,  Germanic  Con- 
gress, American  Electro-Therapeutic  Association,  held  their  annual 
meetings  during  the  week  of  the  Congress,  although  the  date  rendered 
it  impossible  for  the  majority  of  the  associations  to  meet  at  that  time. 
The  eighth  International  Geographic  Congress  adjourned  from  Wash- 
ington to  St.  Louis  to  meet  with  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science.  In 
response  to  the  special  invitations,  two  hundred  forty-seven  ten- 
minute  addresses  were  promised  and  one  hundred  two  actually  read. 

RECEPTION   OF   FOREIGN   GUESTS 

Every  effort  was  made  by  the  Department  of  Congresses  to  assist 
the  foreign  speakers  in  their  traveling  arrangements  and  to  make 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 


21 


matters  as  easy  and  comfortable  as  possible.  A  letter  of  advice  was 
mailed  to  each  speaker  prior  to  his  departure,  carefully  setting  forth 
the  conditions  of  American  travel,  routes  to  be  followed,  reception 
committees  to  be  met,  and  other  essential  details.  The  official  badge 
of  the  Congress  was  also  mailed,  so  that  those  wearing  them  might 
be  easily  identified  by  the  reception  committees  both  in  New  York 
and  St.  Louis.  Nine  tenths  of  the  speakers  cam.e  by  the  way  of  New 
York,  and  in  order  to  facilitate  the  clearance  of  their  baggage  and  to 
provide  for  their  fitting  entertainment  in  New  York,  a  special  recep- 
tion committee  was  formed  composed  of  the  following  members :  — 

F.  P.  Keppel,  Columbia  University,  New  York  City,  Chairman. 
Prof.  Herbert  V.  Abbott,  New  York.     Robert  Hoguet,  New  York. 


R.  Arrowsmith,  New  York. 
C.  William  Beebe,  New  York. 
George  Bendelari,  New  York. 
Edward  W.  Berry,  Passaic. 
J.  Fuller  Berry,  Old  Forge, 
Rev.  H.  C.  Birckhead,  New  York. 
Dr.  James  H.  Canfield,  New  York. 
Rev.  G.  A.  Carstenson,  New  York. 
Prof.  H.  S.  Crampton,  New  York. 
Sanford  L.  Cutler,  New  York. 
Dr.  Israel  Davidson,  New  York. 
William  H.  Davis,  New  York. 
Prof.  James  C.  Egbert,  New  York. 
Dr.  Haven  Emerson,  New  York. 
Prof.  T.  S.  Fiske,  New  York. 
J.  D.  Fitz-Gerald,  II,  Newark. 
W.  D.  Forbes,  Hoboken. 
Clyde  Furst,  Yonkers. 
William  K.  Gregory,  New  York. 
George  CO.  Haas,  New  York. 
Prof.  W.  A.  Hervey,  New  York. 
Carl  Herzog,  New  York. 


Dr.  Percy  Hughes,  Brooklyn. 
Prof.  A.  V.  W.  Jackson,  New  York. 
Albert  J.  W.  Kern,  New  York. 
Prof.  Charles  F.  Kroh,  Orange. 
Dr.  George  F.  Kunz,  New  York. 
Prof.  L.  A.  Lousseaux,  New  York. 
Frederic  L.  Luqueer,  Brooklyn. 
R.  A.  V.  Minckwitz,  New  York. 
Charles  A.  Nelson,  New  York. 
Dr.  Harry  B.  PenhoUow,  New  York. 
Prof.  E.  D.  Perry,  New  York. 
John  Pohhnan,  New  York. 
Dr.  Ernest  Richard,  New  York. 
Dr.  K.  E.  Richter,  New  York. 
Edward  Russ,  Hoboken. 
Prof.  C.  L.  Speranza,  Oak  Ridge. 
Prof.  Francis  H.  Stoddard,  New  York. 
Dr.  Anthony  Spitzka,  Goodground. 
Harvey  W.  Thayer,  Brooldyn. 
Prof.  H.  A.  Todd,  New  York. 
Dr.  E.  M.  Wahl,  New  York. 
Prof.  F.  H.  WUkens,  New  York. 


To  each  foreign  speaker  was  extended  the  courtesies  of  the  Century 
and  the  University  clubs  while  remaining  in  New  York  City,  Mention 
should  also  be  made  of  the  assistance  of  the  Treasury  Department 
and  of  the  courtesy  of  Collector  of  the  Port,  Hon.  N.  N.  Stranahan, 
through  whom  special  privileges  of  the  Port  were  extended  to 
the  members  of  the  Congress.  The  work  of  the  reception  committee 
was  most  satisfactorily  and  efficiently  performed,  and  was  highly 
appreciated  by  the  foreign  guests..  Special  acknowledgment  is  due 
Mr,  F.  P.  Keppel,  of  Columbia  University,  for  his  painstaking  and 
efficient  management  of  the  affairs  of  the  committee  in  New  York, 
Many  of  the  speakers  proceeded  singly  to  St.  Louis,  stopping  at  vari- 
ous places,  but  the  great  majority  went  directly  to  the  University  of 
Chicago,  where  they  were  entertained  during  the  week  preceding  the 
Congress  by  President  Harper  and  Professor  Small,  of  the  University 


22 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 


of  Chicago.  The  arrivals  at  St.  Louis  were  made  on  Saturday  the  17th 
and  Sunday  the  18th  of  September.  Many  of  the  participants  had 
arrived  at  earUer  dates,  and  fully  twenty  of  the  speakers  were  mem- 
bers of  the  International  Jury  of  Awards  for  their  respective  countries, 
and  had  been  in  St.  Louis  since  September  1,  the  beginning  of  the 
Jury  work. 

A  reception  committee  similar  to  that  in  New  York  was  also 
formed  at  St.  Louis  from  the  members  of  the  University  Club,  and 
their  duties  were  to  meet  all  incoming  trains  and  conduct  the  members 
of  the  Congress  personally  to  their  stopping-places,  and  assist  them 
in  all  matters  of  detail.  This  committee  was  comprised  of  the  follow- 
ing members,  nearly  all  of  the  University  Club,  who  performed 
their  work  efficiently  and  enthusiastically  to  the  great  satisfaction 
of  the  Exposition  and  to  the  thorough  appreciation  of  the  foreign 
guests :  — 


V.  M.  Porter,  Chairman,     St.  Louis. 

E.  H.  Angert,  St.  Louis. 

Gouverneur  Calhoun,  St.  Louis. 

W.  M.  Chauvenet,  St.  Louis. 

H.  G.  Cleveland,  St.  Louis. 

Mr.  M.  B.  Clopton,  St.  Louis. 

Walter  Fischel,  St.  Louis. 

W.  L.  R.  Gifford,  St.  Louis. 

E.  M.  Grossman,  St.  Louis. 

L.  W.  Hagerman,  St.  Louis. 

Louis  La  Beaume,  St.  Louis. 


Carl  H.  Lagenburg, 
Sears  Lelimann, 
G.  F.  Paddock, 
T.  G.  Rutledge, 
Luther  Ely  Smith, 
J.  Clarence  Taussig, 
C.  E.  L.  Thomas, 
W.  M.  Tompkins, 
G.  T.  Weitzel, 
Tyrrell  Williams, 


St.  Louis. 
St.  Louis. 
St.  Louis, 
St.  Louis. 
St.  Louis. 
St.  Louis. 
St.  Louis. 
St.  Louis. 
St.  Louis. 
St.  Louis. 


The  itinerary  of  the  foreign  speakers  after  leaving  St.  Louis  at  the 
end  of  the  Congress  took  them  on  appointed  trains  to  Washington, 
where  they  were  given  an  official  reception  by  President  Roosevelt 
and  a  reception  by  Dr.  Simon  Newcomb,  President  of  the  Congress. 
From  here  they  proceeded  to  Harvard  University,  Cambridge,  Mass., 
where  they  were  given  a  reception  by  Prof.  Hugo  Miinsterberg, 
and  were  entertained  as  guests  of  Harvard  University.  Thence  the 
great  majority  of  the  speakers  returned  to  New  York,  where  the}^ 
were  the  guests  of  Columbia  University,  and  were  given  a  farewell 
dinner  by  the  Association  of  Old  German  Students.  Many  of  the 
speakers,  however,  visited  other  portions  of  the  country  before 
returning  to  Europe. 

The  foreign  speakers  while  in  St.  Louis  were  considered  the  guests 
of  the  Exposition  Company,  and  were  relieved  from  all  care  and 
expense  for  rooms  and  entertainment.  Those  who  were  accompanied 
by  their  wives  and  daughters  were  entertained  by  prominent  St.  Louis 
families,  and  those  who  came  singly  were  quartered  in  the  dormitory 
of  the  Washington  University,  which  was  set  aside  for  this  purpose 
during  the  week  of  the  Congress.  The  dormitory  arrangement  proved 
a  very  happy  circumstance,  as  nearly  one  hundred  foreign  and  Amer- 


THE  HISTORY   OF   THE   CONGRESS  23 

ican  scientists  of  the  highest  rank  were  thrown  in  contact,  much  after 
the  fashion  of  their  student  days,  and  thoroughly  enjoyed  the  novelty 
and  fellowship  of  the  plan.  The  dormitory  contained  ninety-six 
rooms  newly  fitted  up  with  much  care  and  with  all  modern  con- 
veniences. Light  breakfasts  were  served  in  the  rooms,  and  special 
service  provided  at  the  call  of  the  occupants.  The  situation  of  the 
dormitory  also  in  the  Exposition  grounds  in  close  proximity  to  the 
assembly  halls  was  highly  appreciated,  and  although  at  times  there 
were  minor  matters  which  did  not  run  so  smoothly,  the  almost 
unanimous  expression  of  the  guests  of  the  Exposition  was  one  of 
delight  and  appreciation  of  the  arrangements.  Special  mention  ought 
in  justice  to  be  made  to  those  residents  of  St.  Louis  who  sustained 
the  time-honored  name  of  the  city  for  hospitality  and  courtesy  by 
entertaining  those  foreign  members  of  the  Congress  who  were  accom- 
panied by  the  immediate  members  of  their  family.  They  were  as 
follows:  — 

Dr.  C.  Barck  Mr.  Edward  Mallinckrodt 

Dr.  William  Bartlett  Mr.  George  D.  Markham 

Judge  W.  F.  Boyle  Mr.  Thomas  McKittrick 

Mr.  Robert  Brookings  Mr.  Theodore  Meier 

Mrs.  J.  T.  Davis  Dr.  S.  J.  Niccolls 

Dr.  Samuel  Dodd  Dr.  W.  F.  Nolker 

Mr.  L.  D.  Dozier  Dr.  S.  J.  Schwab 

Dr.  W.  E.  Fischel  Dr.  Henry  Schwartz 

Mr.  Louis  Fusz  Mr.  Corwin  H.  Spencer 

Mr.  August  Gehner  Dr.  William  Taussig 

Dr.  M.  A.  Goldstein  Mr.  G.  H.  Tenbroek 

Mr.  Charles  H.  Huttig  Dr.  Herman  Tuholske 

Dr.  Ernest  Jonas  Hon.  Rolla  Wells 

Mr.  R.  McKittrick  Jones  Mr.  Edwards  Whitaker 

Mr.  F.  W.  Lehmann  Mr.  Charles  Wuelfing 

Dr.  Robert  Luedeking  Mr.  Max  Wuelfing. 

DETAIL    OF   THE    CONGRESS 

The  immense  amount  of  detail  work  which  devolved  upon  the 
Department  in  the  matter  of  preparing  halls  for  the  meetings,  receiv- 
ing guests,  providing  for  their  comfort,  issuing  the  programmes, 
managing  the  detail  of  the  receptions,  banquets,  invitations,  etc., 
providing  for  registration,  payment  of  honorariums,  and  furnishing 
information  on  every  conceivable  topic,  rendered  necessary  the  for- 
mation of  a  special  bureau  which  was  placed  in  charge  of  Dr.  L.  O. 
Howard  of  Washington,  D.  C,  as  Executive  Secretary.  Dr.  Howard's 
long  experience  as  Secretary  of  the  American  Association  for  the 
Advancement  of  Science  rendered  him  particularly  well  qualified  to 
assume  this  laborious  and  thankless  task.  By  mutual  arrangement 
the  Director  of  Congresses  and  the  Executive  Secretary  divided 
the  field  of  labor.    The  Director  had,  in  addition  to  the  general  over- 


24  THE  HISTORY  OF   THE  CONGRESS 

sight  of  the  Congress,  special  supervision  of  the  local  reception  com- 
mittee, the  entertainment  of  the  guests,  official  banquets  and  enter- 
tainments, and  all  financial  details.  The  Executive  Secretary  took 
entire  charge  of  the  programme,  assignment  of  rooms  in  the  dormi- 
tory, care  and  supervision  of  the  dormitory,  assignment  of  halls  for 
speakers,  registration  books  and  bureau  of  information.  Dr.  Howard 
arrived  on  September  1  to  begin  his  duties,  and  remained  until 
September  30. 

WEEK   OF   THE    CONGRESS 

The  opening  session  of  the  Congress  was  set  for  Monday  afternoon, 
September  19,  at  2.30  o'clock  in  Festival  Hall.  The  main  programme 
of  the  Congress  began  Tuesday  morning.  The  sessions  were  held  in 
the  mornings  and  afternoons,  the  evenings  being  left  free  for  social 
affairs.  The  list  of  functions  authorized  in  honor  of  the  Congress  of 
Arts  and  Science  were  as  follows :  — 

Monday  evening,  September  19,  grand  fete  night  in  honor  of  the 
guests  of  the  Congress,  with  special  musical  programme  about  the 
Grand  Basin  and  lagoons,  boat  rides  and  lagoon  fete;  this  function 
was  unfortunately  somewhat  marred  by  inclement  weather.  It  was 
the  only  evening  free  in  the  entire  week,  however,  for  members  of 
the  Congress  to  witness  the  illuminations  and  decorative  evening 
effects. 

Banquet  given  by  the  St.  Louis  Chemical  Society  at  the  Southern 
Hotel  to  members  of  the  chemical  sections  of  the  Congress. 

Tuesday  evening,  September  20,  general  reception  by  the  Board 
of  Lady  Managers  to  the  officers  and  speakers  of  the  Congress  and 
officials  of  the  Exposition. 

Wednesday  afternoon,  September  21,  garden  fete  given  to  the 
members  of  the  Congress  at  the  French  National  Pavilion  by  the 
Commissioner-General  from  France.  The  gardens  of  the  miniature 
Grand  Trianon  were  never  more  beautiful  than  on  this  brilliant  after- 
noon, and  the  presence  of  the  Garde  Republicaine  band  and  the  entire 
official  representation  of  the  Exposition,  lent  a  color  and  spirit  to  the 
affair  unsurpassed  during  the  Exposition  period. 

Wednesday  evening,  reception  by  the  Imperial  German  Commis- 
sioner-General to  the  officers  and  speakers  of  the  Congress  and  the 
officials  of  the  Exposition,  at  the  German  State  House.  The  magni- 
ficent hospitality  which  characterized  this  building  during  the  entire 
Exposition  period  was  fairly  outdone  on  this  occasion,  and  the  func- 
tion stands  prominent  as  one  of  the  brilliant  successes  of  the  Exposi- 
tion period. 

Thursday  evening,  September  22,  Shaw  banquet  at  the  Bucking- 
ham Club  to  the  foreign  delegates  and  officers  of  the  Congress. 
Through  the  courtesy  of  the  trustees  of  Shaw's  Garden  and  of  the 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS  25 

officers  of  Washington  University,  the  annual  banquet  provided  for 
men  of  science,  letters,  and  affairs,  by  the  will  of  Henry  B.  Shaw, 
founder  of  the  Missouri  Botanical  Gardens,  was  given  during  this 
week  as  a  compliment  to  the  noted  foreign  scientists  who  were  the 
guests  of  the  city  of  St.  Louis. 

Friday  evening,  September  23,  official  banquet  given  by  the 
Exposition  to  the  speakers  and  officials  of  the  Congress  and  the 
officials  of  the  Exposition,  in  the  banquet  hall  of  the  Tyrolean  Alps. 

Saturday  evening,  September  24,  banquet  at  the  St.  Louis  Club 
given  by  the  Round  Table  of  St.  Louis,  to  the  foreign  members  of  the 
Congress.  The  Round  Table  is  a  literary  club  which  meets  at  banquet 
six  times  annually  for  discussion  of  topics  of  interest  to  the  literary 
and  scientific  world. 

Banquet  given  by  the  Imperial  Commissioner-General  from  Japan 
to  the  Japanese  delegation  to  the  Congress  and  to  the  Exposition 
officials  and  Chiefs  of  Departments. 

Dinner  given  by  Commissioner-General  from  Great  Britain  to  the 
English  members  of  the  Congress. 

OPENING    OF   THE    CONGRESS 

The  assembhng  of  the  Congress  on  the  afternoon  of  September  19, 
in  the  magnificent  auditorium  of  Festival  Hall  which  crowned  Cascade 
Hill  and  the  Terrace  of  States,  was  marked  with  simple  ceremonies 
and  impressive  dignity.  The  great  organ  pealed  the  national  hymns 
of  the  countries  participating  and  closed  with  the  national  anthem 
of  the  United  States.  In  the  audience  were  the  members  of  the  Con- 
gress representing  the  selected  talent  of  the  world  in  their  field  of 
scientific  endeavor,  and  about  them  were  grouped  an  audience  drawn 
from  every  part  of  the  United  States  to  promote  by  their  presence  the 
success  of  the  Congress  and  to  do  honor  to  the  noted  personages  who 
were  the  guests  of  the  Exposition  and  of  the  Nation.  On  the  stage 
were  seated  the  officials  of  the  Congress,  the  honorary  vice-presidents 
from  foreign  nations,  and  the  officials  of  the  Exposition. 

At  the  appointed  hour  the  Director  of  Congresses,  Dr.  Howard  J. 
Rogers,  called  the  meeting  to  order,  and  outlined  in  a  few  words  the 
object  of  the  Congress,  welcomed  the  foreign  delegates,  and  presented 
the  members,  both  foreign  and  American,  to  the  President  of  the 
Exposition,  Hon.  David  R.  Francis. 

The  President  spoke  as  follows :  — 

What  an  ambitious  undertaking  is  a  universal  exposition!  But  how  worthy 
it  is  of  the  highest  effort!  And,  if  successful,  how  far-reaching  are  its  results, 
how  lasting  its  benefits!  Who  shall  pass  judgment  on  that  success?  On  what 
evidence,  by  what  standards  shall  their  verdicts  be  formed?  The  development 
of  society,  the  advancement  of  civilization,  involve  many  problems,  encounter 
many  and  serious  difficulties,  and  have  met  with  deplorable  reactions  which 
decades  and  centuries  w^e  required  to  repair.    The  proper  study  of  mankind  is 


26  THE   HISTORY   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

man,  and  any  progress  in  science  that  ignores  or  loses  sight  of  his  welfare  and 
happiness,  however  admirable  and  wonderful  such  progress  may  be,  disturbs  the 
equilibrium  of  society. 

The  tendency  of  the  times  toward  centralization  or  unification  is,  from  an 
economic  standpoint,  a  drifting  in  the  right  direction,  but  the  piloting  must  be 
done  by  skillful  hands,  under  the  supervision  and  control  of  far-seeing  minds,  who 
will  remember  that  the  masses  are  human  beings  whose  education  and  expanding 
intelligence  are  constantly  broadening  and  emphasizing  their  individuality.  A 
universal  exposition  affords  to  its  visitors,  and  those  who  systematically  study  its 
exhibits  and  its  phases,  an  unequaled  opportunity  to  view  the  general  progress  and 
development  of  all  countries  and  all  races.  Every  line  of  human  endeavor  is  here 
represented. 

The  conventions  heretofore  held  on  these  grounds  and  many  planned  to  be 
held  —  aggregating  over  three  hundred  —  have  been  confined  in  their  delibera- 
tions to  special  lines  of  thought  or  activity.  This  international  congress  of  arts 
and  sciences  is  the  most  comprehensive  in  its  plan  and  scope  of  any  ever  held, 
and  is  the  first  of  its  kind.  The  lines  of  its  organization,  I  shall  leave  the  Director 
of  Exhibits,  who  is  also  a  member  of  the  administrative  board  of  this  congress,  to 
explain.  You  who  are  members  are  already  advised  as  to  its  scope,  and  your 
almost  universal  and  prompt  acceptance  of  the  invitations  extended  to  you  to 
participate,  implies  an  approval  which  we  appreciate,  and  indicates  a  willingness 
and  a  desire  to  cooperate  in  an  effort  to  bring  into  intelligent  and  beneficial  corre- 
lation all  branches  of  science,  all  lines  of  thought.  You  need  no  argument  to  con- 
vince you  of  the  eminent  fitness  of  making  such  a  congress  a  prominent  feature 
of  a  universal  exposition  in  which  education  is  the  dominant  feature. 

The  administrative  board  and  the  organizing  committee  have  discharged  their 
onerous  and  responsible  tasks  with  signal  fidelity  and  ability,  and  the  success  that 
has  rewarded  their  efforts  is  a  lasting  monument  to  their  wisdom.  The  manage- 
ment of  the  Exposition  tenders  to  them,  collectively  and  individually,  its  grateful 
acknowledgments.  The  membership  in  this  congress  represents  the  world's  elect 
in  research  and  in  thought.  The  participants  were  selected  after  a  careful  survey 
of  the  entire  field  ;  no  limitations  of  national  boundaries  or  racial  affiliations 
have  been  observed.  The  Universal  Exposition  of  1904,  the  city  of  St.  Louis, 
the  Louisiana  territory  whose  acquisition  we  are  celebrating,  the  entire  country, 
and  all  participating  in  or  visiting  this  Exposition  are  grateful  for  your  coming, 
and  feel  honored  by  your  presence. 

We  are  proud  to  welcome  you  to  a  scene  where  are  presented  the  best  and  high- 
est material  products  of  all  countries  and  of  every  civilization,  participated  in  by 
all  peoples,  from  the  most  primitive  to  the  most  highly  cultured  —  a  marker  in  the 
progress  of  the  world,  and  of  which  the  International  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science 
is  the  crowning  feature. 

May  the  atmosphere  of  this  universal  exposition,  cliarged  as  it  is  mth  the 
restless  energies  of  every  phase  of  human  activity  and  permeated  by  that  ineffable 
sentiment  of  universal  brotherhood  engendered  by  the  intelligent  sons  of  God,  con- 
gregating for  the  friendly  rivalries  of  peace,  inspire  you  with  even  higher  thoughts 
—  imbue  you  with  still  broader  sympathies,  to  the  end  that  by  your  future  labors 
you  may  be  still  more  helpful  to  the  human  race  and  place  your  fellow  men  under 
yet  deeper  obligations. 

Director  Frederick  J.  V.  Skiff  was  then  introduced  by  the  Presi- 
dent as  representing  the  Division  of  Exhibits,  whose  untiring  labors 
had  filled  the  magnificent  Exposition  palaces  surrounding  the  Festival 
Hall  with  the  visible  products  of  those  sciences  and  arts,  the  theory, 


THE  HISTORY  OF   THE  CONGRESS  27 

progress,    and  problems  of  which   the  Congress  was  assembled  to 
consider. 

Mr.  Skiff  spoke  as  follows :  — 

The  division  of  exhibits  of  the  Universal  Exposition  of  1904  has  looked  for- 
ward to  this  time,  when  the  work  it  has  performed  is  to  be  reviewed  and  discussed 
by  this  distinguished  body.  I  do  not,  of  course,  intend  to  convey  the  idea  that 
the  international  congress  is  to  inspect  or  criticise  the  exhibitions,  but  I  do  mean 
to  say  that  the  deliberations  of  this  organization  are  contemporaneous  with  and 
share  the  responsibility  for  the  accomplishments  of  which  the  exhibitions  made 
are  the  visible  evidences. 

The  great  educational  yield  of  a  universal  exposition  comes  from  the  intellec- 
tual more  than  from  the  mechanical  processes.  It  is  the  material  condition  of  the 
times.  It  is  as  weU  the  duty  of  the  responsible  authorities  to  go  yet  further  and 
record  the  thoughts  and  theories,  the  investigations,  experiments,  and  observa- 
tions of  which  these  material  things  are  the  tangible  results. 

A  congress  of  arts  and  science,  whose  membership  is  drawn  from  aU  educational 
as  well  as  geographical  zones,  not  only  accounts  for  and  analyzes  the  philosophy 
of  conditions,  but  points  the  way  for  further  advance  along  the  lines  consistent 
with  demonstration.  Its  contribution  to  the  hour  is  at  once  a  history  and  a 
prophecy. 

The  extent  to  which  the  deliberations  and  utterances  of  this  congress  may 
regulate  the  development  of  society  or  give  impulse  to  succeeding  generations,  it 
is  impossible  to  estimate,  but  not  unreasonable  to  anticipate.  The  plans  of  the 
congress  matured  in  the  minds  of  the  best  scholars;  the  classification  of  its  pur- 
pose, the  scope,  the  selection  of  its  distinguished  participants,  gave  to  the  hopes 
and  ambitions  of  the  management  of  the  Exposition  inspiration  of  a  most  exalted 
degree.  At  first  these  ambitions  were  —  not  without  reason  —  regarded  as  too 
high.  The  plane  upon  which  the  congress  had  been  inaugurated,  the  aim,  the 
broad  intent,  seemed  beyond  the  merits,  if  not  beyond  the  capacity,  of  this  liitherto 
not  widely  recognized  intellectual  centre.  But  the  courage  of  the  inception,  the 
loftiness  of  the  purpose,  appealed  so  profoundly  to  the  toilers  for  truth  and  the 
apostles  of  fact,  that  we  find  gathered  here  to-day  in  the  heart  of  the  new  Western 
continent  the  great  minds  whose  impress  on  society  has  rendered  possible  the  intel- 
lectual heights  to  which  this  age  has  ascended  and  now  beckon  forward  the  stu- 
dents of  the  world  to  limitless  possibilities. 

While  international  congresses  of  literature,  science,  art,  and  industry  have  been 
accomplished  by  previous  expositions,  yet  to  classify  and  select  the  topics  in  sym- 
pathy with  the  classification  and  installation  of  the  exhibits  material  is  a  step 
considerably  in  advance  of  the  custom.  The  men  who  build  an  exposition  must 
by  temperament,  if  not  by  characteristic,  be  educators.  They  must  be  in  sym- 
pathy with  the  welfare  of  humanity  and  its  higher  destiny.  The  exhibitions  at  this 
Exposition  are  not  the  haphazard  gatherings  of  convenient  material,  but  the  out- 
come of  a  plan  to  illustrate  the  productiveness  of  mankind  at  this  particular  time, 
carefully  digested,  thoroughly  thought  out,  and  conscientiously  executed.  The 
exhibit,  therefore,  in  each  of  the  departments  of  the  classification,  as  well  as  in  the 
groups  of  the  different  departments,  are  of  such  character,  and  so  arranged  as  to 
reflect  the  best  that  the  world  can  do  along  departmental  lines,  and  the  best  that 
different  peoples  can  do  along  group  lines.  The  congresses  accord  with  the  ex- 
hibits, and  the  exhibits  give  expression  to  the  congresses. 

Education  has  been  the  keynote  of  this  Exposition.  Were  it  not  for  the  educa- 
tional idea,  the  acts  of  government  providing  vast  sums  of  money  for  the  up- 
building of  this  Exposition  would  have  been  impossible.  This  congress  reflects 
one  idea  vastly  outstripping  others,  and  that  is,  in  the  unity  of  thought  in  the 


28  THE  HISTORY   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

universal  concert  of  purpose.  It  is  the  first  time,  I  believe,  that  there  has  been  an 
international  gathering  of  the  authorities  of  all  the  sciences,  and  in  that  respect 
the  congress  initiates  and  establishes  the  universal  brotherhood  of  scholars. 

A  thought  uncommunicated  is  of  little  value.  An  unrecorded  achievement 
is  not  an  asset  of  society.  The  real  lasting  value  of  this  congress  wiU  consist  of  the 
printed  record  of  its  proceedings.  The  delivery  of  the  addresses,  reaching  and 
appealing  to,  as  must  necessarily  be  the  case,  a  very  limited  number  of  people, 
can  be  considered  as  only  a  method  of  reaching  the  lasting  and  perpetual  good  of 
civilization. 

In  just  the  degree  that  this  Exposition  in  its  various  divisions  shall  make  a 
record  of  accomplishments,  and  lead  the  way  to  further  advance,  this  enterprise 
has  reached  the  expectations  of  its  contributors  and  the  hopes  of  its  promoters. 
This  congress  is  the  peak  of  the  mountain  that  this  Exposition  has  builded  on 
the  highway  of  progress.  From  its  heights  we  contemplate  the  past,  record  the 
present,  and  gaze  into  the  future. 

This  universal  exposition  is  a  world's  university.  The  International  Congress 
of  Arts  and  Science  constitutes  the  faculty;  the  material  on  exhibition  are  the 
laboratories  and  the  museums;  the  students  are  mankind. 

That  in  response  to  invitation  of  the  splendid  committee  of  patriotic  men,  to 
whom  all  praise  is  due  for  their  efforts  in  this  crowning  glory  of  the  Exposition,  so 
eminent  a  gathering  of  the  scholars  and  savants  of  the  world  has  resulted,  speaks 
unmistakably  for  the  fraternity  of  the  world,  for  the  sympathy  of  its  citizenship, 
and  for  the  patriotism  of  its  people. 

In  reply  to  these  addresses  of  the  officials  of  the  Exposition,  the 
honorary  Vice-Presidents  for  Great  Britain,  France,  Germany,  Rus- 
sia, Austria,  Italy,  and  Japan  made  brief  responses  in  behalf  of  their 
respective  countries. 

Sir  William  Ramsay  of  London  spoke  in  the  place  of  Hon.  James 
Bryce,  extending  England's  thanks  for  the  courtesy  which  had  been 
shown  her  representatives  and  declaring  that  England,  particularly 
in  the  scientific  field,  looked  upon  America  as  a  relative  and  not  as 
a  foreign  country. 

France  was  represented  by  Professor  Jean  Gaston  Darboux,  Per- 
petual Secretary  of  the  Academy  of  Sciences  of  Paris,  who  spoke  as 
follows :  — 

Mr.  President,  Ladies  and  Gentlemen,  —  My  first  word  wiU  be  to  thank 
you  for  the  honor  which  you  have  been  so  courteous  as  to  pay  my  country  in 
reserving  for  her  one  of  the  vice-presidencies  of  the  Congress.  Since  the  time  of 
Franklin,  who  received  at  the  hands  of  France  the  welcome  which  justice  and  his 
own  personal  genius  and  worth  demanded,  most  affectionate  relations  have  not 
ceased  to  unite  the  scientists  of  France  and  the  scientists  of  America.  The  dis- 
tinction which  you  have  here  accorded  to  us  will  contribute  stiU  further  to  render 
these  relations  more  intimate  and  more  fraternal.  In  choosing  me  among  so  many 
of  the  better  fitted  delegates  sent  by  my  country,  you  have  without  doubt  wished 
to  pay  special  honor  to  the  Academic  des  Sciences  and  to  the  Institut  de  France, 
which  I  have  the  honor  of  representing  in  the  position  of  Perpetual  Secretary. 
Permit  me  therefore  to  thank  you  in  the  name  of  these  great  societies,  which  are 
happy  to  count  in  the  number  of  their  foreign  associates  and  of  their  correspond- 
ents so  many  of  the  scholars  of  America.  In  like  manner  as  the  Institut  de  France, 
so  the  Congress  which  opens  to-day  seeks  to  unite  at  the  same  time  letters,  science, 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS  29 

and  arts.  We  shall  be  happy  and  proud  to  take  part  in  this  work  and  contribute 
to  its  success. 

Germany  was  represented  by  Professor  Wilhelm  Waldeyer,  of  the 
University  of  Berlin,  who  replied  as  follows:  — 

Mk.  President,  Honored  Assemblage,  —  The  esteemed  invitation  which  has 
been  offered  to  me  in  this  significant  hour  of  the  opening  of  the  Congress  of  Arts 
and  Science  to  greet  the  members  of  this  congress,  and  particularly  my  esteemed 
compatriots,  I  have  had  no  desire  to  decline.  I  have  been  for  a  fortnight  imder 
the  free  sky  of  this  mighty  city  —  so  I  must  express  myself,  since  enclosing  walls 
are  unknown  in  the  United  States  —  and  this  fact,  together  with  the  hospitality 
offered  me  in  such  delightful  manner  by  the  Chairman  of  the  Committee  on  Con- 
gresses, Mr.  Frederick  W.  Lehmann,  has  almost  made  me  a  St.  Louis  man.  There- 
fore I  may  perhaps  take  it  upon  myseff  to  greet  you  here. 

I  confess  that  I  arrived  here  with  some  misgiving  —  some  doubts  as  to  whether 
the  great  task  which  was  here  imdertaken  under  most  difficult  circumstances 
could  be  accomplished  with  even  creditable  success.  These  doubts  entirely  dis- 
appeared the  first  time  I  entered  the  grounds  of  the  World's  Fair  and  obtained  a 
general  view  of  the  method,  beautiful  as  well  as  practical,  by  which  the  treasures 
gathered  from  the  whole  world  were  arranged  and  displayed.  I  trust  you,  too,  will 
have  a  like  experience;  and  will  soon  recognize  that  a  most  earnest  and  good  work 
is  here  accomplished. 

And  I  must  remark  at  this  time  that  we  Germans  may  indeed  be  well  satisfied 
here;  the  unanimous  and  complete  recognition  which  our  cooperation  in  this 
great  work  has  received  is  almost  disconcerting. 

What  can  be  said  of  the  whole  Exposition  with  reference  to  its  extent  and  the 
order  in  which  everything  is  arranged,  I  may  well  say  concerning  the  depart- 
ments of  science,  especially  interesting  to  us.  In  this  hour  in  which  the  Congress 
of  Arts  and  Science  is  being  opened,  we  shall  not  express  any  thanks  to  those  who 
took  this  part  of  the  work  upon  their  shoulders — a  more  difficult  task  indeed  than 
all  the  others,  for  here  the  problem  is  not  to  manage  materials,  but  heads  and 
minds.  And  as  I  see  here  assembled  a  large  number  of  German  professors  —  I,  too, 
belong  to  the  profession  —  of  whom  it  is  said,  I  know  not  with  how  much  justice, 
that  they  are  hard  to  lead,  the  labors  of  the  Directors  and  Presidents  of  the 
Congress  could  not  have  been,  and  are  not  now,  small.  Neither  shall  we  to-day 
prophesy  into  what  the  Congress  may  develop.  The  greater  number  of  speakers 
cannot  expect  to  have  large  audiences,  but  even  to-day  we  can  safely  say  this :  the 
imposing  row  of  volumes  in  which  shall  be  given  to  posterity  the  reviews  here  to 
be  presented  concerning  the  present  condition,  and  future  problems  of  the  sciences 
and  arts  as  they  appear  to  the  scientific  world  at  the  beginning  of  the  twentieth 
century,  will  provide  a  mommaental  work  of  lasting  value.  This  we  may  confi- 
dently expect.  The  thanks  which  we  to-day  do  not  wish  to  anticipate  in  words,  let 
us  show  by  our  actions  to  our  kind  American  hosts,  and  especially  to  the  directors 
of  the  World's  Fair  and  of  this  Congress.  With  exalted  mind,  forgetting  all  little 
annoyances  which  may  and  will  come,  let  us  go  forward  courageously  to  the  work, 
and  let  us  do  our  best.  Let  us  grasp  heartily  the  open  hand  honestly  extended  to 
us. 

May  this  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science  worthily  take  part  in  the  great  and 
undisputed  success  which  even  to-day  we  must  acknowledge  the  World's  Fair 
at  St.  Louis. 

For  Austria  Dr.  Theodore  Escherich,  of  the  University  of  Vienna, 
responded  as  follows :  — 


30  THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

In  the  name  of  the  many  Austrians  present  at  the  Congress  I  express  the  thanks 
of  my  compatriots  to  the  Committee  which  summoned  us,  for  their  invitation  and 
the  hospitality  so  cordially  extended.   .   .   . 

I  congratulate  the  authorities  upon  the  idea  of  opening  this  Congress.  How 
many  world-expositions  have  already  been  held  without  an  attempt  having  been 
made  to  exhibit  the  spirit  that  has  created  this  world  of  beautiful  and  useful 
things  ?  It  was  reserved  for  these  men  to  find  the  form  in  which  the  highest  results 
of  human  thought  —  Science  —  represented  in  the  persons  of  her  representatives, 
could  be  incorporated  in  the  compass  of  the  World's  Fair.  The  conception  of  this 
International  Congress  of  all  Sciences  in  its  originality  and  audacity,  in  its  univer- 
sality and  comprehensive  organization,  is  truly  a  child  of  the  "  young-American 
spirit."  .  .  . 

After  this  Congress  has  come  to  a  close  and  the  collection  of  the  lectures  de- 
livered, an  unparalleled  encyclopaedia  of  human  knowledge,  both  in  extent  and 
content,  will  have  appeared.  We  may  say  that  this  Fair  has  become  of  epochal 
importance,  not  alone  for  trade  and  manufactures,  but  also  for  science.  These 
proud  palaces  wiU  long  have  disappeared  and  been  forgotten  when  this  work,  a 
monumentum  aere  perennius,  shaU  still  testify  to  future  generations  the  standard 
of  scientific  attainment  at  the  beginning  of  the  twentieth  century. 

Short  acknowledgments  were  then  made  for  Russia  by  Dr.  Oscar 
Backlund,  of  the  Astronomical  Observatory  at  Pulkowa,  Russia,  and 
for  Japan  by  Prof.  Nobushige  Hozumi,  of  the  Imperial  University  at 
Tokio,  Japan. 

The  last  of  the  Vice-Presidents  to  respond  to  the  addresses  of  wel- 
come was  Signor  Attilio  Brunialti,  Councilor  of  State  for  Italy,  who 
after  a  few  formal  words  in  English  broke  into  impassioned  eloquence 
in  his  native  tongue,  and  in  brilliant  diction  and  graceful  periods 
expressed  the  deep  feeling  and  profound  joy  which  Italy,  the  mother 
of  arts,  felt  in  participating  in  an  occasion  so  historic  and  so  magni- 
ficent.   Signor  Brunialti  said  in  part :  — 

I  thank  you,  gentlemen,  for  the  honor  you  have  paid  both  to  my  country  and 
myself  by  electing  me  a  Vice-President  of  this  great  scientific  assembly.  Would 
that  I  could  thank  you  in  words  in  which  vibrate  the  heart  of  Rome,  the  scientific 
spirit  of  my  land,  and  aU  that  it  has  given  to  the  world  for  the  progress  of  science, 
literature,  and  art.  You  know  Italy,  gentlemen,  you  admire  her,  and  therefore 
it  is  for  this  also  that  my  thanks  are  due  to  you.  What  ancient  Rome  has  con- 
tributed to  the  common  patrimony  of  civilization  is  also  refiected  here  in  a  thou- 
sand ways,  and  a  classical  education,  held  in  such  honor,  by  a  young  and  practical 
people  such  as  yours,  excites  our  admiration  and  also  our  astonisliment.  By  giant 
strides  you  are  reviving  the  activity  of  Italy  at  the  epoch  of  the  Communes,  when 
all  were  animated  by  unwearying  activity  and  our  manufactures  and  arts  held 
the  first  place  in  Europe.  I  have  already  praised  here  the  courageous  spirit  which 
has  suggested  the  meeting  of  this  Congress  —  a  Congress  that  will  remain  famous 
in  the  annals  of  science.  Many  things  in  your  country  have  aroused  in  me  grow- 
ing surprise,  but  nothing  has  struck  me  more,  I  assure  you,  than  this  homage  to 
science  which  is  pushing  aU  the  wealthy  classes  to  a  noble  rivalry  for  the  increase 
of  education  and  mental  cultivation. 

You  have  already  large  libraries  and  richly  endowed  universities,  and  every 
kind  of  school,  where  the  works  of  Greece  and  Rome  are  perhaps  even  more  appre- 
ciated and  adapted  to  modern  improvements  than  with  us  old  classical  nations. 


THE   HISTORY   OF   THE   CONGRESS     '  31 

Full  of  energy,  activity,  and  wealth,  you  have  before  you  perpetual  progress,  and 
what,  up  to  this,  your  youth  has  not  allowed  you  to  give  to  the  world,  you  will 
surely  be  able  to  give  in  the  future.  Use  freely  all  the  treasures  of  civilization,  art, 
and  science  that  centuries  have  accumulated  in  the  old  world,  and  especially  in 
my  beloved  Italy;  fructify  them  with  your  youthful  initiation  and  with  your 
powerful  energy.  By  so  doing  you  will  contribute  to  peace,  and  then  we  may  say 
with  truth  that  we  have  prepared  your  route  by  the  work  of  centuries;  and  like 
unto  those  who  from  old  age  are  prevented  from  following  the  bold  young  man 
of  Longfellow  in  his  course,  we  will  accompany  you  with  our  greetings  and  our 
alterable  affection. 

By  my  voice,  the  native  country  of  Columbus,  of  Galileo,  of  Michelangelo  and 
Raphael,  of  Macchiavelli  and  Volta,  salutes  and  with  open  arms  hails  as  her  hope- 
ful daughter  young  America,  —  thanking  and  blessing  her  for  the  road  she  has 
opened  to  the  sons  of  Italy,  workmen  and  artists,  to  civilization,  to  science,  and  to 
modem  research  and  thought. 

The  Chairman  of  the  Administrative  Board,  President  Nicholas 
Murray  Butler,  of  Columbia  University,  was  prevented  by  illness  in 
his  family  from  being  present  at  the  Congress,  and  in  place  of  the 
address  to  have  been  delivered  by  him  on  the  idea  and  development 
of  the  Congress  and  the  work  of  the  Administrative  Board,  President 
William  R.  Harper,  of  the  University  of  Chicago,  spoke  on  the  same 
subject  as  follows:  — 

I  have  been  asked  within  a  few  hours  by  those  in  authority  to  present  to  you 
on  behalf  of  the  Administrative  Board  of  this  International  Congress  a  statement 
concerning  the  origin  and  purpose  of  the  congress.  It  is  surely  a  source  of  great 
disappointment  to  all  concerned  that  the  chairman  of  the  board.  President  Butler, 
is  prevented  from  being  present. 

Many  of  us  recall  the  fact  that  at  the  Paris  Exposition  of  1889  the  first  attempt 
was  made  to  do  something  systematic  in  the  way  of  congresses.  This  attempt  was 
the  natural  outcome  of  the  opinion  which  had  come  to  exist  that  so  splendid  an 
opportunity  as  was  afforded  by  the  coming  together  of  leaders  in  every  depart- 
ment of  activity  should  not  be  suffered  to  pass  by  unimproved.  What  could  be 
more  natural  in  the  stimulating  and  thought-provoking  atmosphere  of  an  exposi- 
tion than  the  proposal  to  make  provision  for  a  consideration  and  discussion  of 
some  of  the  problems  so  closely  related  to  the  interests  represented  by  the  exposi- 
tion? 

The  results  achieved  at  the  Paris  Exposition  of  1889  were  so  striking  as  to  lead 
those  in  charge  of  the  World's  Columbian  Exposition  in  Chicago,  1893,  to  organize 
what  was  called  the  World's  Congress  Auxiliary,  including  a  series  of  congresses, 
in  which,  to  use  the  language  of  the  original  decree,  "  the  best  workers  in  general 
science,  philosophy,  literature,  art,  agriculture,  trade,  and  labor  were  to  meet  to 
present  their  experiences  and  results  obtained  in  all  those  various  lines  of  thought 
up  to  the  present  time."  Seven  years  later,  in  connection  with  the  Paris  Exposition 
of  1900,  there  was  held  another  similar  series  of  international  congresses.  The 
general  idea  had  in  this  way  slowly  but  surely  gained  recognition. 

The  authorities  of  the  Universal  Exposition  at  St.  Louis,  from  the  first,  recog- 
nized the  desirability  of  providing  for  a  congress  which  should  exceed  in  its  scope 
those  that  had  before  been  attempted.  In  the  earliest  days  of  the  preparation  for 
this  Exposition  Mr.  Frederick  J.  V.  Skiff,  the  Director  of  the  Field  Columbian 
Museum,  my  nearest  neighbor  in  the  city  of  Chicago,  took  occasion  to  present  this 
idea,  and  particularly  to  emphasize  the  specific  point  that  something  should  be 


32  •     THE   HISTORY   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

undertaken  which  not  only  might  add  dignity  and  glory  to  the  great  name  of  the 
Exposition,  but  also  constitute  a  permanent  and  valuable  contribution  to  the 
sum  of  human  knowledge.  After  a  consideration  of  the  whole  question,  which 
extended  over  many  months,  the  committee  on  international  congresses  resolved 
to  establish  an  administrative  board  of  seven  members,  to  which  should  be  com- 
mitted the  responsibility  of  suggesting  a  plan  in  detail  for  the  attainment  of  the 
ends  desired.  This  Board  was  appointed  in  November,  1902,  and  consisted  of 
President  Nicholas  Murray  Butler,  of  Columbia  University,  New  York;  President 
R.  H.  Jesse,  of  the  University  of  Missouri;  President  Henry  S.  Pritchett,  of  the 
Massachusetts  Institute  of  Technology;  Dr.  Herbert  Putnam,  Librarian  of  Con- 
gress; Mr.  Frederick  J.  V.  Skiff,  of  the  Field  Columbian  Museum,  Chicago;  Fred- 
erick G.  Holls,  of  New  York  City,  and  the  present  speaker. 

This  Board  held  several  meetings  for  the  study  of  the  questions  and  problems 
involved  in  the  great  undertaking.  Much  valuable  counsel  was  received  and  con- 
sidered. The  Board  was  especially  indebted,  however,  to  Prof.  Hugo  Miinsterberg 
of  Harvard  University  for  specific  material  which  he  placed  at  their  disposal  — 
material  which,  with  modification,  served  as  the  basis  of  the  plans  adopted  by  the 
Board,  and  reconunended  to  the  members  of  the  Exposition. 

At  the  same  time  the  Administrative  Board  recommended  the  appointment  of 
Dr.  Howard  J.  Rogers  as  the  Director  of  Congresses,  and  nominated  Prof.  Simon 
Newcomb  of  the  United  States  Navy  to  be  President  of  the  Congress,  and  Pro- 
fessors Hugo  Miinsterberg  of  Harvard  University  and  Albion  W.  Small  of  the 
University  of  Chicago  to  be  Vice-Presidents  of  the  Congress;  the  three  to  consti- 
tute the  Organizing  Committee  of  the  Congress.  This  Organizing  Committee  was 
later  empowered  to  visit  foreign  countries  and  to  extend  personal  invitations  to  men 
distinguished  in  the  arts  and  sciences  to  participate  in  the  Congress.  The  recep- 
tion accorded  to  these,  our  representatives,  was  most  cordial.  Of  the  150  invita- 
tions thus  extended,  117  were  accepted;  and  of  the  117  learned  savants  who 
accepted  the  invitation,  96  are  here  in  person  this  afternoon  to  testify  by  their  pre- 
sence the  interest  they  have  felt  in  this  great  concourse  of  the  world's  leaders.  I 
am  compelled  by  necessity  this  afternoon  to  omit  many  points  of  interest  in  rela- 
tion to  the  origin  and  history  of  the  undertaking,  all  of  which  will  be  published  in 
due  time. 

After  many  months  of  expectancy  we  have  at  last  come  together  from  aU  the 
nations  of  the  world.  But  for  what  purpose?  I  do  not  know  that  to  the  statement 
already  published  in  the  programme  of  the  Congress  anything  can  be  added  which 
wiU  really  improve  that  statement.  The  purpose,  as  it  has  seemed  to  some  of  us, 
is  threefold: 

In  the  first  place,  to  secure  such  a  general  survey  of  the  various  fields  of  learn- 
ing, with  aU  their  "subdivisions  and  multiplication  of  specialties,"  as  will  at  the 
same  time  set  forth  their  mutual  relations  and  connections,  and  likewise  constitute 
an  effort  toward  the  unification  of  knowledge.  This  idea  of  unity  has  perhaps  been 
uppermost  in  the  minds  of  all  concerned  with  the  work  of  organizing  the  Congress. 

In  the  second  place,  to  provide  a  platform  from  which  might  be  presented  the 
various  problems,  a  solution  of  wliich  wiU  be  expected  of  the  scholarship  of  the 
future.  This  includes  a  recognition  of  the  fundamental  principles  and  conception 
that  underlie  these  mutual  relations,  and  therefore  serve  necessarily  as  the  basis 
of  all  such  future  work.  Here  again  the  controlling  idea  is  that  of  unity  and  law, 
in  other  words,  universal  law. 

In  the  third  place,  to  bring  together  in  person  and  spirit  distinguished  investi- 
gators and  scholars  from  all  the  countries  of  the  world,  in  order  that  by  contact  of 
one  with  another  a  mutual  sympathy  may  be  promoted,  and  a  practical  coopera- 
tion may  be  effected  among  those  whose  lifework  leads  them  far  apart.  Here,  still 
again,  unity  of  result  is  sought  for. 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS  33 

As  we  now  take  up  the  work  of  this  convention,  which  abeady  gives  sure 
promise  of  being  notable  among  the  conventions  that  have  called  together  men 
of  different  nations,  let  us  confidently  assure  ourselves  that  the  great  purpose 
which  has  throughout  controlled  in  the  different  stages  of  its  organization  will  be 
realized;  that  because  the  Congress  has  been  held,  the  nations  of  the  earth  will 
find  themselves  drawn  more  closely  together;  that  human  thought  will  possess 
a  more  unified  organization  and  human  life  a  more  unified  expression. 

Following  these  addresses  of  welcome  and  of  response  came  the 
first  paper  of  the  specific  programme,  designed  to  be  introductory  to 
the  division,  department,  and  section  addresses  of  the  week.  This 
address,  which  will  be  found  in  full  in  its  proper  place,  on  pages  135  to 
147  of  this  volume,  was  given  by  Dr.  Simon  Newcomb,  President  of 
the  Congress  and  Chairman  of  the  Organizing  Committee,  whose 
labors  for  fifteen  months  were  thus  brought  to  a  brilliant  conclusion. 

At  the  close  of  Dr.  Newcomb 's  address  the  assembly  was  dismissed 
by  a  few  words  of  President  Francis,  in  which  he  placed  at  the  disposi- 
tion of  the  members  of  the  Congress  the  courtesies  and  privileges  of 
the  Exposition,  and  expressed  the  hope  and  belief  that  their  presence 
and  the  purpose  for  which  they  were  assembled,  would  be  the  crown- 
ing glory  of  the  Universal  Exposition  of  1904. 

On  Tuesday,  September  20,  the  seven  division  addresses  and  the 
twenty-four  department  addresses  were  given,  all  the  speakers  being 
Americans  :  Royce,  in  Normative  Science;  Wilson,  in  Historical 
Science;  Woodward,  in  Physical  Science;  Hall,  in  Mental  Science; 
Jordan,  in  Utilitarian  Science;  Lowell,  in  Social  Regulation;  and 
Harris,  in  Social  Culture,  treating  the  main  divisions  of  science  and 
their  applications,  each  dwelling  particularly  on  the  scope  of  the  great 
field  included  in  his  address  and  the  unification  of  the  work  therein. 
The  forty-eight  department  speakers  divided  the  field  of  knowledge, 
one  address  in  each  department  giving  the  fundamental  conceptions 
and  methods,  the  other  the  history  and  development  of  the  work  of 
the  department  during  the  last  century. 

With  Wednesday  the  international  participation  began,  and  in  the 
one  hundred  twenty-eight  sections  into  which  the  departments  were 
divided  one  half  of  the  speakers  were  drawn,  so  far  as  circum- 
stances permitted,  from  foreign  scientific  circles.  With  the  exception 
of  the  last  two  sections,  Religious  Influence  Personal,  and  Religious 
Influence  Social,  the  work  of  the  Congress  closed  on  Saturday  after- 
noon. These  two  sections  having  four  speakers  each  were  placed,  one 
on  Sunday  morning  and  one  on  Sunday  afternoon,  in  Festival  Hall, 
and  passes  to  the  grounds  given  upon  application  to  any  one  desiring 
to  attend.  Large  numbers  availed  themselves  of  the  privilege,  and  the 
closing  hours  of  the  Congress  were  eminently  suitable  and  worthy  of 
its  high  success.  At  the  end  of  the  afternoon  session  in  Festival  Hall, 
Vice-President  of  the  Congress,  Dr.  Albion  W.  Small,  reviewed  in  a 
few  words  the  work  of  the  week,  its  meaning  to  science,  its  possible 


34  THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

effect  upon  American  thought,  and  then  formally  announced  the 
Congress  closed. 

OFFICIAL   BANQUET 

The  official  banquet  given  by  the  Exposition  to  all  participants, 
members,  and  officials  of  the  Congress,  on  Friday  evening,  at  the 
Tyrolean  Alps  banquet  hall,  proved  a  charming  conclusion  to  the 
labors  of  the  week.  No  better  place  could  be  imagined  for  holding  it, 
within  the  grounds  of  an  exposition,  than  the  magnificently  propor- 
tioned music  and  dining  hall  of  the  "Alps."  A  room  160  feet  by  105 
feet,  capable  of  seating  fifteen  hundred  banqueters;  the  spacious, 
oval,  orchestral  stage  at  the  south  end;  the  galleries  and  boxes  along 
the  sides  of  the  hall  done  in  solid  German  oak;  the  beautiful  and 
impressive  mural  decorations,  the  work  of  the  best  painters  of  Ger- 
many; the  excellence  of  the  cuisine,  and  the  thoroughly  drilled  corps 
of  waiters,  rendered  the  physical  accessories  of  a  banquet  as  nearly 
perfect  as  possible  in  a  function  so  extensive. 

The  banquet  was  the  largest  held  during  the  Exposition  period, 
eight  hundred  invitations  being  issued  and  nearly  seven  hundred 
persons  present.  The  music  was  furnished  by  the  famous  Garde 
Republicaine  Band  of  France,  as  the  Exposition  orchestra  was 
obliged  to  fill  its  regular  weekly  assignment  at  Festival  Hall,  The 
decorations  of  the  hall,  the  lights  and  flowers,  the  musical  pro- 
gramme, the  galleries  and  boxes  filled  with  ladies  representing  the 
official  and  social  life  of  the  Exposition,  and  the  distinguished  body 
of  the  Congress,  formed  a  picture  which  appealed  to  the  admiration 
and  enthusiasm  of  every  one  alike.  No  attempt  was  made  to  assign 
seats  to  the  banqueters  outside  the  speakers'  table,  and  little  coteries 
and  clusters  of  scientists,  many  of  whom  were  making  acquaintances 
and  intellectual  alliances  during  this  week  which  would  endure  for 
a  lifetime,  were  scattered  about  the  hall,  giving  an  interest  and  an  ani- 
mation to  the  scene  quite  beyond  the  powers  of  description.  In  one 
corner  were  Harnack,  Budde,  Jean  Reville,  and  Cuthbert  Hall,  chat- 
ting as  animatedly  as  though  their  religious  theories  were  not  as  far 
apart  as  the  poles;  in  another,  Waldeyer,  Escherich,  Jacobi,  Allbutt, 
and  Eatasato  formed  a  medical  group,  the  counterpart  of  which  would 
be  hard  to  find  unless  in  another  part  of  this  same  hall;  still  again 
were  Erdmann,  Sorley,  Ladd,  Royce,  and  Creighton  as  the  centre  of 
a  group  of  philosophers  of  world  renown.  So  in  every  part  of  the 
picture  which  met  the  eye  were  focused  the  leaders  of  thought  and 
action  in  their  respective  fields.  The  tout  ensemble  of  the  Congress  was 
here  brought  out  in  its  strongest  effect,  as,  with  the  exception  of  the 
opening  exercises  at  Festival  Hall  at  which  time  many  had  not  arrived , 
it  was  the  only  time  when  the  entire  membership  was  together.  The 
banquet  coming  at  the  close  of  the  week  was  also  fortunate,  as  by  this 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS  35 

time  the  acquaintances  made,  and  the  common  incidents  and  anec- 
dotes experienced,  heightened  the  enjoyment  of  all. 

The  toastmaster  of  the  banquet  and  presiding  officer,  Hon.  David 
R.  Francis,  was  never  in  a  happier  vein  than  when  he  assumed  the 
gavel  and  proposed  the  health  of  the  President  of  the  United  States 
and  the  rulers  of  all  nations  represented  at  the  board. 

President  Francis  said :  — 

Members  op  the  International  Congress  op  Arts  and  Science  : 

On  the  fa9ade  at  the  base  of  the  Louisiana  Monument,  which  is  the  central 
feature  of  this  Exposition  picture,  is  a  group  of  Livingston,  Monroe,  and  Marbois. 
It  represents  the  signing  of  the  treaty,  which  by  peaceful  negotiation  transferred 
an  empire  from  France  to  the  United  States.  Upon  the  inscription  are  the  words 
of  Livingston,  "  We  have  lived  long  and  accompUshed  much,  but  this  is  the 
crowning  act  of  our  lives." 

It  is  that  transfer  of  an  empire  which  this  Exposition  is  held  to  commemo- 
rate. And  paraphrasing  the  words  of  Livingston,  permit  me  to  say  that  I  have 
presided  over  many  dinners,  but  this  is  the  crowning  act  of  my  career. 

In  opening  the  deUberations  of  the  International  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science, 
I  made  the  statement  that  a  Universal  Exposition  is  an  ambitious  undertaking. 
I  stated  also  that  the  International  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science  is  the  crowning 
feature  of  this  Exposition.  I  did  not  venture  the  assertion  then  which  I  have  the 
presumption  to  make  now,  that  the  most  difficult  task  in  connection  with  this 
Universal  Exposition  was  the  assembling  of  an  International  Congress  of  Arts 
and  Science.  I  venture  to  make  the  statement  now,  because  I  feel  that  I  am  justi- 
fied in  doing  so  by  the  success  which  up  to  the  present  has  attended  your  delibera- 
tions. Any  congregation  of  the  leaders  of  thought  in  the  world  is  a  memorable 
occasion.  This  is  the  first  systematic  one  that  has  ever  been  attempted.  Whether 
it  proves  successful  or  not,  it  will  be  long  remembered  in  the  history  of  the  civilized 
countries  that  have  participated  in  it.  If  it  be  but  the  precursor  of  other  like 
assemblages  it  wiU  stiU  be  long  remembered,  and  in  that  event  it  wiU  be  entitled 
to  unspeakable  credit  if  it  accomplishes  anything  toward  the  realization  of  the 
very  laudable  objects  which  prompted  its  assembhng. 

The  effort  to  unify  aU  human  knowledge  and  to  establish  the  inter-relations 
thereof  is  a  bold  conception,  and  requires  the  courage  that  characterizes  the 
people  who  live  in  the  western  section  of  the  United  States.  If  it  be  the  last  effort 
of  the  kind  it  will  still  be  remembered,  and  this  Universal  Exposition,  if  it  had 
done  nothing  else  to  endear  it  to  cultured  people  of  this  and  other  countries,  will 
not  be  forgotten.  The  savants  assembled  by  the  caU  of  this  Exposition  have  pur- 
sued their  respective  lines  of  thought  and  research,  prompted  by  no  desire  other 
than  one  to  find  a  solution  of  the  problem  which  confronts  humanity.  By  bringing 
you  together  and  making  an  effort  to  determine  and  establish  the  relations  between 
all  lines  of  human  knowledge,  we  have  certainly  made  an  advance  in  the  right 
direction.  If  your  researches,  if  the  results  of  your  studies,  can  be  utilized  by 
the  human  race,  then  we  who  have  been  the  instruments  of  that  great  blessing 
wiU  be  entitled  to  credit  secondary  only  to  the  men  who  are  the  discoverers  of 
the  scientific  knowledge  whose  relations  we  are  endeavoring  to  establish.  The 
Management  of  the  Universal  Exposition  of  1904  salutes  the  International  Con- 
gress of  Arts  and  Science.  We  drink  to  the  perpetuation  of  that  organization,  and 
I  shall  caU  upon  its  distinguished  President,  Professor  Newcomb,  to  respond  to 
the  sentiment. 

Dr.  Newcomb  in  a  few  words  thanked  the  members  of  the  Congress 


36  THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

for  their  participation,  which  had  made  possible  the  brilliant  success 
of  the  enterprise,  portrayed  its  effect  and  the  influence  of  its  perpetua- 
tion, and  then  extended  to  all  the  invitation  from  the  President  of 
the  United  States  to  attend  the  reception  at  the  White  House  on  the 
following  Tuesday. 

In  responding  to  these  toasts  the  senior  Honorary  Vice-President, 
Hon.  James  Bryce,  of  Great  Britain,  spoke  in  matchless  form  and 
held  the  attention  of  the  vast  hall  closely  while  he  portrayed  in  a  few 
words  the  chief  glories  of  England  in  the  field  of  science,  and  the 
pride  the  English  nation  felt  in  the  glorious  record  made  by  her 
eldest  daughter,  the  United  States,  Mr.  Bryce  spoke  extempora- 
neously, and  his  remarks  cannot  be  given  in  full. 

For  Germany,  Commissioner-General  Lewald  responded  in  an 
eloquent  address,  in  which,  after  thanking  the  Exposition  and  the 
American  Government  for  the  high  honor  done  the  German  nation  in 
selecting  so  large  a  percentage  of  the  speakers  from  German  scien- 
tific circles,  he  enlarged  upon  the  close  relations  which  had  existed 
between  German  university  thought  and  methods  and  American 
thought  and  practice,  due  to  the  vast  number  of  American  students 
who  had  pursued  their  post-graduate  courses  in  the  universities  of 
Germany.  He  dwelt  upon  the  pride  that  Germany  felt  in  this  sincerest 
form  of  tribute  to  German  supremacy  in  scientific  thought,  and  of  the 
satisfaction  which  the  influence  in  this  country  of  German-trained 
students  afforded.  He  described  at  length  the  great  exhibit  made  by 
German  universities  in  the  education  department  of  the  Exposition, 
and  pointed  to  it  as  demonstrating  the  supremacy  of  German  scienti- 
fic thought  and  accurate  methods.  Dr.  Lewald  closed  with  a  brilliant 
peroration,  in  which  he  referred  to  the  immense  service  done  for  the 
cause  of  science  in  the  last  fifty  years  of  German  history  and  to  the 
patronage  and  support  of  the  Emperor,  not  only  to  science  in  general, 
but  to  this  great  international  gathering  of  scientific  experts,  and 
drank  to  the  continued  cordial  relations  of  Germany  and  America 
through  its  university  circles  and  scientific  endeavors. 

For  the  response  from  France,  Prof.  Gaston  Darboux  was  dele- 
gated by  Commissioner-General  Gerald,  who  was  unable  to  be  present 
on  account  of  sickness.  In  one  of  the  most  beautiful  and  polished 
addresses  of  the  evening.  Professor  Darboux  spoke  in  French,  of  which 
the  following  is  a  translation :  — 

Gentlemen,  —  Graciously  invited  to  respond  in  the  name  of  the  delegates 
of  France  who  have  accepted  the  invitation  of  the  American  Government,  I  con- 
sider it  my  duty  in  the  first  place  to  thank  this  great  nation  for  the  honor  which 
it  has  paid  to  us,  and  for  the  welcome  which  it  has  extended  to  us.  Those  of  you 
who  are  doing  me  the  honor  to  listen,  know  of  that  disagreeable  feeling  of  isolation 
which  at  times  the  traveler  in  the  midst  of  a  strange  people  experiences;  —  that 
feeling  I  know  only  from  hearsay.  We  have  not  had  a  moment  of  time  to  experi- 
ence it.   They  are  accustomed  in  Europe  to  portray  the  Americans  as  exclusively 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS  37 

occupied  with  business  affairs.  They  throw  in  our  faces  the  famous  proverb/  Busi- 
ness is  Business/  and  give  it  to  us  as  the  rule  of  conduct  for  Americans.  We  are 
able  to  testify  entirely  to  the  contrary,  since  the  inhabitants  of  this  beautiful  coun- 
try are  always  seeking  to  extend  to  strangers  a  thousand  courtesies.  Above  aU,  we 
have  encountered  no  one  who  has  not  been  anxious  to  go  out  of  his  way  to  give 
to  us,  even  before  we  had  asked  it,  such  information  as  it  was  necessary  for  us  to 
have.  And  what  shall  I  say  of  the  welcome  which  we  have  received  here  at  the 
hands  of  our  American  confreres,  —  Monsieur  the  President  of  the  Exposition, 
Monsieur  the  Director  of  Congresses  and  other  worthy  colaborers?  The  authori- 
ties of  the  Exposition  and  the  inhabitants  of  St.  Louis  have  rivaled  each  other  in 
making  our  stay  agreeable  and  our  ways  pleasant  in  the  heart  of  this  magnificent 
Exposition,  of  which  we  shall  ever  preserve  the  most  enchanting  memory. 

We  should  have  wished  to  see  in  a  more  leisurely  manner,  and  to  make 
acquaintance  with  the  attractions  without  number  with  which  the  Exposition 
literally  swarms  (men  of  letters  and  men  of  science  love  at  times  to  disport 
themselves)  and  to  study  the  exhibits  classified  in  a  method  so  exact  in  the 
palaces  of  an  architecture  so  original  and  so  impressive.  But  Monsieur  Newcomb 
has  not  permitted  this.  The  Congress  of  which  he  is  the  illustrious  President  offers 
so  much  in  the  way  of  attractions,  —  of  a  kind  a  little  rigorous  it  is  true,  —  and  so 
much  of  work  to  be  accomplished,  that  to  our  very  great  regret  we  have  had  to 
refuse  many  invitations  which  it  would  have  been  most  agreeable  to  accept.  The 
Americans  wiU  pardon  us  for  this,  I  am  sure;  they  know  better  than  any  one  else 
the  value  of  time,  but  they  know  also  that  human  strength  has  some  limits,  espe- 
cially among  us  poor  Europeans,  for  I  doubt  whether  an  American  ever  knows 
the  meaning  of  fatigue. 

Messieurs,  the  Congress  which  is  about  to  terminate  to-morrow  has  been  truly 
a  very  great  event.  It  is  the  first  time,  I  beUeve,  that  there  has  been  seen  assembled 
in  one  grand  international  reunion  that  which  our  great  minister,  Colbert,  had  in 
mind,  and  that  which  we  have  realized  for  the  first  time  in  our  Institut  de  France, 
—  the  union  of  letters,  science,  and  arts.  That  this  union  shall  maintain  itself  in 
the  future  is  the  dearest  wish  of  my  heart. 

Science  is  a  unit,  even  as  the  Universe.  The  aspects  which  it  presents  know 
neither  boundaries  of  states  nor  the  pohtical  divisions  established  between  peoples . 
In  all  civilized  countries  they  calculate  with  the  same  figures,  they  measure  with 
the  same  instruments,  they  employ  the  same  classifications,  they  study  the  same 
historic  facts,  economics,  and  morals.  If  there  exists  among  the  different  nations 
some  differences  in  methods,  these  differences  are  slight.  They  are  a  benefit  at  the 
same  time  as  well  as  a  necessity.  For  the  doing  of  the  immense  amount  of  work 
of  research  imposed  on  that  part  of  humanity  which  thinks,  it  is  necessary  that 
the  subjects  of  study  should  not  be  identically  the  same,  or  better,  if  they  are 
identical,  that  the  difference  between  the  points  of  view  from  which  they  are  con- 
sidered in  the  different  countries  contribute  to  our  better  knowledge  of  their 
nature,  their  results,  and  their  applications.  It  is  necessary  then  that  each  people 
preserve  their  distinctive  genius,  their  particular  methods  which  they  use  to 
develop  the  qualities  they  have  inherited.  In  exactly  the  same  way  that  it  is 
important  in  an  orchestra  that  each  instrument  play  in  the  most  perfect  manner, 
and  with  the  timbre  which  accords  with  its  nature,  the  part  which  is  given  to  it, 
so  in  science  as  in  music,  the  harmony  between  the  players  is  a  necessary  condi- 
tion, which  each  one  ought  to  exert  himself  to  realize.  Let  us  endeavor  then  in 
scientific  research  to  execute  in  the  most  perfect  manner  that  part  of  the  task 
which  fate  has  devolved  upon  us,  but  let  us  endeavor  also  to  maintain  that  accord 
which  is  a  necessary  condition  to  the  harmony  which  wiU  alone  be  able  in  the 
future  to  assure  the  progress  of  humanity. 

Gentlemen,  in  this  international  reunion  it  would  not  be  fitting  that  I  dwell 


38  THE  HISTORY   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

upon  the  services  which  my  country  has  been  able  to  render  to  science;  and  on 
the  other  hand  it  would  be  difficult  for  me  to  say  to  you  exactly  what  part  America 
is  called  upon  to  take  in  this  concert  of  civilized  nations ;  but  I  am  certain  that  the 
part  wiU  be  worthy  of  the  great  nation  which  has  given  to  itself  a  constitution  so 
hberal  and  which  in  so  short  a  space  of  time  has  known  how  to  conquer,  and 
measure  in  value,  a  territory  so  immense  that  it  extends  from  ocean  to  ocean.  I 
lift  my  glass  to  the  honor  of  American  science;  I  drink  to  the  future  of  that  great 
nation,  for  which  we,  as  weU  as  aU  other  Frenchmen,  hold  so  much  of  common 
remembrance,  so  much  of  close  and  Uving  sympathy,  and  so  much  of  profound 
admiration.  I  am  the  more  happy  to  do  this  in  this-  most  beautiful  territory  of 
Louisiana,  which  France  in  a  former  age  ceded  freely  to  America. 

Perhaps  the  treat  of  the  evening  was  the  response  made  in  behalf 
of  the  Empire  of  Japan  by  Professor  Hozumi,  of  the  Faculty  of  Law 
of  the  University  of  Tokio. 

Unfortunately  this  response  was  not  preserved  in  full,  but  Professor 
Hozumi  dwelt  with  much  feeling  on  the  world-wide  significance  of  the 
Congress  and  the  common  plane  upon  which  all  nations  might  meet 
in  the  pursuit  of  science  and  the  manifold  applications  of  scientific 
principles.  He  paid  a  beautiful  tribute  to  the  educational  system  of  the 
United  States  and  to  the  great  debt  which  Japan  owed  to  American 
scholars  and  to  American  teachers  for  their  aid  in  establishing  mod- 
ern educational  principles  and  methods  in  the  Empire  of  Japan.  The 
impetus  given  to  scientific  study  in  Japan  by  the  Japanese  students 
trained  in  American  universities  was  also  earnestly  dwelt  upon,  and 
the  close  relations  which  had  always  existed  between  Japanese  and 
American  students  and  instructors  feelingly  described.  In  the  field 
of  science  Japan  was  yet  young,  but  she  had  shown  herself  a  close 
and  apt  pupil,  and  her  period  of  initiative  and  original  research  was 
at  hand.  In  bacteriology,  in  medicine,  in  seismology,  oceanography, 
and  other  fields,  Japan  has  made  valuable  contributions  to  science 
and  established  the  right  to  recognition  in  an  international  gathering 
of  this  nature.  It  was  with  peculiar  and  grateful  pride  and  pleasure 
that  the  Japanese  Government  had  sent  its  delegation  to  this  Con- 
gress of  selected  experts  in  response  to  the  invitation  of  the  American 
Government.  Near  the  close  of  his  address  Professor  Hozumi  made 
a  gracious  and  happy  allusion,  based  upon  the  conflict  with  Russia, 
in  which  he  said  that  of  all  places  where  men  meet,  and  of  all  places 
sunned  by  the  light  of  heaven,  this  great  Congress,  built  on  the  high 
plane  of  the  brotherhood  of  science  and  the  fellowship  of  scholars, 
was  the  only  place  where  a  Japanese  and  a  Russian  could  meet  in 
mutual  accord,  with  a  common  purpose,  and  clasp  hands  in  unity  of 
thought.  This  chivalrous  and  beautiful  idea,  given  here  so  imper- 
fectly from  memory,  brought  the  great  assembly  to  its  feet  in  rounds 
of  cheers.  In  closing,  Professor  Hozumi  expressed  the  earnest  belief 
that  the  benefits  of  science  from  a  gathering  of  this  nature  would 
quickly  be  felt,  by  a  closer  cooperation  in  the  application  of  theory 


THE  HISTORY   OF   THE  CONGRESS  39 

and  practical  principles  and  a  simultaneous  advance  in  all  parts  of  the 
world. 

The  closing  response  of  the  evening  for  the  foreign  members  was 
made  for  Italy  by  Signor  Attilio  Brunialti,  whose  brilliant  eloquence 
at  many  times  during  the  week  had  won  the  admiration  of  the  mem- 
bers of  the  Congress.  Under  the  inspiration  of  this  assemblage  he 
fairly  surpassed  himself,  and  the  following  translation  of  his  remarks 
but  poorly  indicates  the  grace  and  brilliant  diction  of  the  original :  — 

I  have  had  the  good  fortune  to  be  present  in  this  wonderful  country  at  three 
international  Congresses,  that  of  science,  the  peace  parliament,  and  the  geo- 
graphic. I  wish  to  record  the  impression  they  have  excited  in  my  mind,  already  so 
favorably  inchned  by  your  never-to-be-forgotten  and  gracious  reception.  You 
must,  please,  allow  me  to  address  you  in  my  own  language,  because  the  Latin 
tongue  inspires  me,  because  I  wish  to  affirm  more  solemnlj^  my  nationality,  and 
also,  because  I  cannot  express  my  feelings  weU  in  a  language  not  familiar  to  me. 
My  country,  the  land  of  Columbus,  of  GaUleo,  the  nation  that  more  than  all  others 
in  Europe  is  an  element  of  peace,  is  already  in  itself  the  synthesis  of  the  three 
Congresses.  And  I  can  caU  to  mind  that  tliis  land  is  indebted  to  geography  for 
the  fact  of  its  being  made  kno-mi  to  the  world,  because  the  immortal  Genoese 
pointed  it  out  to  people  fighting  in  the  old  world  for  a  small  territory,  and  opened 
to  mortals  new  and  extensive  countries  destined  to  receive  the  valiant  and  the 
audacious  of  the  entire  world  and  to  rise  like  yours  to  immortal  glory. 

Thus  the  poet  can  sing,  — 

L'  avanza,  1'  avanza 
Divino  straniero, 
Conosci  la  stanza 
Che  i  fati  ti  diero; 
Se  lutti,  se  lagrime 
Ancora  rinterra 
L'  giovin  la  terra. 

Thus  Columbus  of  old  could  point  out  to  men  —  who  run  down  each  other, 
disputing  even  love  for  fear  that  man  may  become  a  wolf  for  man  —  the  vast 
and  endless  wastes  awaiting  laborers,  and  give  to  man  the  treasures  of  the  fruit- 
ful land.  'Tis  in  the  name  of  peace  that  I  greet  modern  science  in  all  its  forms, 
and  I  say  to  you  chemists:  "Invent  new  means  of  destruction;"  and  to  you 
mechanics  and  shipbuilders:  "  Give  us  invulnerable  men-of-war  and  such  per- 
fect caimons,  that  your  owti  progress  may  contribute  to  make  war  rarer  in  the 
world."  Then  will  men,  amazed  at  their  own  destructive  progress,  be  drawn 
together  by  brotherly  love,  by  the  development  of  common  knowledge  and 
sympathy,  and  by  the  study  of  geography  be  led  to  know  that  there  is  plenty  of 
room  for  every  one  in  the  world  to  contribute  to  progress  and  civilization. 

Americans!  these  sentiments  are  graven  in  your  country;  in  point  of  fact,  it  is 
a  proof  of  the  harmony  that  reigns  in  this  Congress  between  guests  come  from  all 
parts  of  the  world,  that  I,  an  Italian,  am  allowed  to  address  you  in  my  own  lan- 
guage on  American  ground,  near  the  Tyrolean  Alps,  greeted  by  the  music  of  the 
Republicaine  French  Garde,  united  in  eternal  bonds  of  friendship  by  the  two 
great  goddesses  of  the  modern  world,  —  Science  and  Peace. 

The  last  speaker  of  the  evening  was  Hon.  Frederick  W.  Lehmann, 
Chairman  of  the  Exposition  Committee  on  Congresses,  who  in  elo- 
quent periods  set  forth  the  ambition  of  the  city  of  St.  Louis  and  the 


40  THE   HISTORY  OF   THE   CONGRESS 

Exposition  of  190-1  in  creating  a  Congress  of  intellect  on  the  same  high 
plane  that  had  characterized  the  educational  ideals  of  the  Exposition,. 
and  the  intense  satisfaction  which  the  officials  of  the  Congress  felt  in 
its  brilliant  outcome,  and  the  possibilities  which  it  promised  for  an 
unequaled  contribution  to  scientific  hterature. 

At  the  close  of  these  addresses  the  members  of  the  Congress  and 
the  spectators  in  the  gallery  sang,  in  full  chorus  and  under  the  lead  of 
the  Garde  Repubhcaine  Band,  the  various  national  anthems,  closing 
with  "The  Star  Spangled  Banner." 

PUBLICATION    OF   THE   REPORT 

In  accordance  with  the  recommendation  of  the  Administrative 
Board  to  the  Committee  on  Congresses,  the  Executive  Committee 
appointed  Dr.  Howard  J.  Rogers,  Director  of  Congresses,  editor  of 
the  proceedings  of  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science.  The  Congress 
records  were  removed  from  St.  Louis  to  Albany,  Xew  York,  the  home 
of  the  Director,  from  which  place  the  pubHcation  has  been  prepared. 
Upon  collecting  the  papers  it  was  found  that  they  could  be  di'V'ided 
logically,  and  with  a  fair  degree  of  similarity  in  size,  into  eight  volumes, 
each  of  which  should  cover  a  definite  and  distinct  portion  of  the  pro- 
gramme.    These  are  as  follows :  — 

Volume  1.  History  of  the  Congress,  Scientific  Plan  of  the  Congress. 

Philosophy,  Mathematics. 
Volume  2.   Pohtical  and  Economic  Hjstorv^,  Histor}'  of  Law,  History 

of  Rehgion. 
Volume  3.  History  of  Language,  History  of  Literature,  History  of 

Art. 
Volume  4.   Physics,  Chemistry,  Astronomy,  Sciences  of  the  Earth. 
Volume  5.   Biolog}-,  Anthropology,  Psychology,  Sociology. 
Volume  6.   Medicine,  Technology. 

Volimie  7.   Economics,  PoUtics,  Jurisprudence,  Social  Science. 
Volume  8.   Education,  Rehgion. 

The  details  and  specifications  of  the  volumes  were  prepared  for 
competitive  bids  and  submitted  to  twelve  of  the  prominent  pubUsh- 
ers  of  the  country.  The  most  advantageous  bid  was  received  from 
Houghton,  ^lifflin  &  Company  of  Boston,  Mass.,  and  was  accepted 
by  the  Exposition  Company.  The  Administrative  Board  and  the 
authorities  of  the  Exposition  feel  deeply  pleased  at  the  result,  inas- 
much as  the  imprint  of  this  firm  guarantees  a  work  in  fuU  accord  with 
the  high  plane  upon  which  the  Congress  has  been  conducted. 

It  was  determined  to  print  the  entire  proceedings  in  the  English 
language,  inasmuch  as  the  Congress  was  held  in  an  English-speaking 
countr}-  and  the  vast  majority  of  the  papers  were  read  in  that  lan- 
guage.   The  consent  of  ever}"-  foreign  speaker  was  obtained  for  this 


THE  HISTORY  OF   THE  CONGRESS  41 

procedure.  It  was  found,  after  collecting,  that  the  number  of  addresses 
to  be  translated  was  forty-four.  The  translators  were  selected  by 
the  editor  upon  the  advice  of  the  members  of  the  Administrative 
Board  and  Organizing  Committee,  and  great  care  was  taken  to  find 
persons  not  only  thoroughly  trained  in  the  two  languages  and  pos- 
sessing a  good  EngUsh  style,  but  also  persons  who  were  thoroughly 
conversant  with  the  subject  on  which  the  paper  treated.  Many  of 
the  translators  were  suggested  by  the  foreign  speakers  themselves. 
As  a  result  of  this  careful  selection,  the  editor  feels  confident  that  the 
original  value  of  the  papers  has  been  in  no  wise  detracted  from,  and 
that  both  in  form  and  content  the  translations  are  thoroughly  satis- 
factory. 

It  wall  be  found  that  some  addresses  are  not  closely  related  to  the 
scheme  of  the  Congress.  Either  through  some  misunderstanding  of  the 
exact  purpose  of  the  Congress,  or  through  too  close  devotion  to  their 
own  particular  phase  of  investigation,  some  half-dozen  speakers  sub- 
mitted papers  deaUng  with  special  lines  of  work.  These,  while  valu- 
able and  scholarly  from  their  standpoint,  do  not  accord  with  a  series 
of  papers  prepared  with  a  view  to  general  relations  and  historical 
perspective.  The  exceptions  are  so  few,  however,  as  not  seriously  to 
interfere  -^ith  the  unity  of  the  plan. 

In  the  arrangement  of  the  papers  the  order  of  the  official  pro- 
gramme is  followed  exactly,  with  the  exception  that,  under  Historical 
Science,  Departments  3,  4,  and  8,  covering  Histor}^  of  Politics,  Law, 
and  Religion,  are  combined  in  one  volume;  and  Departments  5,  6, 
and  7,  covering  History  of  Language,  Literature,  and  Art,  are  com- 
bined in  the  succeeding  volume.  In  volume  one,  the  first  chapter  is 
devoted  to  the  history  of  the  Congress,  T\Titten  by  the  editor,  in  which 
is  set  forth  the  plain  narrative  of  the  growth  and  development  of 
the  Congress,  as  much  for  the  benefit  of  similar  undertakings  in  the 
future  as  for  the  interest  of  those  participating  in  this  Congress.  The 
second  chapter  contains  the  scientific  introduction,  written  by  Prof. 
Hugo  Miinsterberg  of  Harvard  University,  First  Vice-President  of 
the  Congress  and  Member  of  the  Organizing  Committee.  This  is 
written  for  the  purpose  of  giving  in  detail  the  principles  upon  which 
the  classification  was  based,  and  the  relations  which  the  different 
sections  and  departments  held  to  each  other. 

_  Each  paper  is  prefaced  by  a  very  short  biographical  note  in  cate- 
gorical form,  for  the  purpose  of  insuring  the  identity  of  the  speaker 
as  long  in  the  future  as  the  volumes  may  exist.  Appended  to  the  ad- 
dresses of  each  department  is  a  short  bibliography,  which  is  essential 
for  a  general  study  of  the  subject  in  question.  These  are  in  no  wise 
exhaustive  or  complete,  but  are  rather  designed  to  be  a  small,  valu- 
able, working  reference  Hbrary  for  students.  The  bibliographies  have 
been  prepared  by  eminent  experts  in  the  departments  of  the  Con- 


42  THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

gress,  but  are  necessarily  somewhat  uneven,  as  some  of  the  writers 
have  gone  into  the  subject  more  thoroughly  than  others.  The  general 
arrangement  of  the  bibliographies  is:  1.  Historical  books  and  stand- 
ard works  dealing  with  the  subject.  2.  General  books  for  the  whole 
department.  3.  Books  for  sections  of  departments. 

Appended  also  to  the  addresses  of  each  department  and  sections 
are  resumes  of  the  ten-minute  addresses  delivered  by  invitation  at 
the  meeting  of  the  department  or  section.  Many  of  these  papers  are  of 
high  value;  but  inasmuch  as  very  few  of  them  were  written  in  accord 
with  the  plan  of  the  Congress,  and  with  the  main  thought  to  be  de- 
veloped by  the  Congress,  but  deal  rather  with  some  interesting  and 
detached  phase  of  the  subject,  it  has  been  deemed  best  not  to  print 
them  in  full,  but  to  indicate  in  brief  the  subject  and  the  treatment 
given  it  by  the  writer.  Those  which  do  accord  with  the  plan  of  the 
Congress  are  given  more  extensive  treatment. 

CONCLUSION 

What  the  results  of  the  Congress  will  be;  what  influence  it  may 
have;  was  it  worth  the  work  and  cost,  are  questions  often  fairly  asked. 

The  lasting  results  and  influences  are  of  course  problematical. 
They  depend  upon  the  character  and  soundness  of  the  addresses,  and 
whether  the  uniform  strength  of  the  publication  will  make  the  work 
as  a  whole,  what  it  undoubtedly  is  in  parts,  a  source-book  for  the 
future  on  the  bases  of  scientific  theory  at  the  beginning  of  the  twenti- 
eth century,  and  a  reliable  sketch  of  the  growth  of  science  during  the 
nineteenth  century.  Critical  study  of  the  addresses  will  alone  deter- 
mine this,  but  from  the  favorable  reception  of  those  already  pub- 
lished in  reviews,  and  from  editorial  acquaintance  with  the  others, 
it  seems  assured.  That  portion  of  the  section  addresses  which  deals 
with  the  inter-relations  of  science  and  demonstrates  both  its  unity 
and  variety  of  processes  is  new  and  authoritative  thought,  and  will  be 
the  basis  of  much  discussion  and  remodeling  of  theories  in  the  future. 

The  immediate  results  of  the  Congress  are  highly  satisfactory, 
and  fully  repay  the  work  and  the  cost  both  from  a  scientific  and  an 
exposition  standpoint.  As  an  acknowledgment  of  the  prominence 
of  scientific  methods,  as  a  public  recognition  of  the  work  of  scientists, 
as  the  means  of  bringing  to  one  place  the  most  noted  assemblage  of 
thinkers  the  world  has  ever  seen,  as  an  opportunity  for  scholars  to 
meet  and  know  each  other  better,  the  Congress  was  an  unqualified 
success  and  of  enduring  reputation.  From  the  Exposition  point  of 
view,  it  was  equally  a  success;  not  financially,  nor  was  there  ever 
a  thought  that  it  would  be.  Probably  not  more  than  seven  thousand 
persons  outside  of  St.  Louis  came  primarily  to  attend  the  Congress, 
and  their  admission  fees  were  a  bagatelle;  the  revenue  derived  from 
the  sale  of  the  Proceedings  will  not  meet  the  cost  of  printing.   There 


THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS  43 

has  been  no  money  value  sought  for  in  the  Congress,  —  none  received. 
Its  value  to  the  Exposition  lies  solely  in  the  fact  that  it  is  the  final 
argument  to  the  world  of  the  initial  claims  of  the  officials  of  the 
Exposition  that  its  purpose  was  purely  educational.  Coordinate  with 
the  material  exhibits,  sought,  classified,  and  installed  on  a  rigidly 
scientific  classification,  the  Congress,  which  relates,  illumines,  and 
defends  the  principles  upon  which  the  material  portion  was  founded, 
has  triumphantly  vindicated  the  good  faith,  the  wisdom,  and  the 
foresight  of  the  Universal  Exposition  of  1904.  This  printed  record  of 
its  proceedings  will  be  a  monument  not  only  to  the  spirit  of  Science, 
but  to  the  spirit  of  the  Exposition,  which  will  endure  as  long  as  the 
records  of  man  are  preserved. 

In  conclusion,  the  editor  wishes  to  express  his  obligations  to  the 
many  speakers  and  officers  of  the  Congress,  who  have  evinced  great 
interest  in  the  publication  and  assisted  by  valuable  suggestions  and 
advice.  In  particular,  he  acknowledges  the  help  of  President  Butler 
of  Columbia  University,  Professor  Miinsterberg  of  Harvard  Uni- 
versity, and  Professor  Small  of  the  University  of  Chicago.  Acknow- 
ledgments are  with  justice  and  pleasure  made  to  the  Committee  on 
Congresses  of  the  Exposition,  and  the  able  chairman,  Hon.  Frederick 
W.  Lehmann,  for  their  unwavering  and  prompt  support  on  aU  mat- 
ters of  policy  and  detail,  without  which  the  full  measure  of  success 
could  not  have  been  achieved.  To  the  efficient  secretary  of  the 
Department  of  Congresses,  Mr.  James  Green  Cotchett,  an  expression 
of  obligation  is  due  for  his  indefatigable  labors  during  the  Congress 
period,  and  for  his  able  and  painstaking  work  in  compiling  the 
detailed  records  of  this  publication. 

At  a  meeting  of  the  Executive  Committee  of  the  Exposition  on 
January  3,  1905,  there  was  unanimously  voted  the  following  resolu- 
tion, recommended  by  the  Administrative  Board  and  approved  by 
the  Committee  on  Congresses :  — 

Moved  :  that  a  vote  of  thanks  and  an  expression  of  deepest  obliga- 
tion be  tendered  to  Dr.  Simon  Newcomb,  President  of  the  Congress, 
Prof.  Hugo  Miinsterberg,  vice-president  of  the  Congress,  and  Prof. 
Albion  W.  Small,  vice-president  of  the  Congress,  for  their  efficient, 
thorough,  and  comprehensive  work  in  connection  with  the  pro- 
gramme of  the  Congress,  the  selection  and  invitation  of  speakers, 
and  the  attention  to  detail  in  its  execution.  That,  in  view  of  the 
enormous  amount  of  labor  devolving  upon  these  three  gentlemen 
for  the  past  eighteen-  months,  to  the  exclusion  of  all  opportunities 
for  literary  and  other  work  outside  their  college  departments,  an 
honorarium  of  twenty-five  hundred  dollars  be  tendered  to  each  of 
them. 


44  THE  HISTORY  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

At  a  subsequent  meeting  the  following  resolution  was  also  passed : — 
Moved  :  that  the  Directors  of  the  Louisiana  Purchase  Exposition 
Company  place  upon  the  record  an  expression  of  their  appreciation 
of  the  invaluable  aid  so  freely  given  by  the  Administrative  Board 
of  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science.  In  organization,  guidance,  and 
results  the  Congress  was  the  most  notable  of  its  kind  in  history. 
For  the  important  part  performed  wisely  and  zealously  by  the  Admin- 
istrative Board  the  Exposition  Management  extends  this  aeknow- 
ledgment. 

SUMMARY  OF  EXPENSES  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

Office  expenses $7,025  82 

Travel 3,847  24 

Exploitation,  Organizing  Committee  abroad     .     .     ,     8,663  16 

Traveling  expenses,  American  Speakers 31,350 

Traveling  expenses.  Foreign  Speakers 49,000 

Honorariums 7,500 

Banquet 3,500 

Expenses  for  editing  proceedings     . 5,875 

Estimated  cost  of  printing  proceedings    .....  22,000  $138,761  22 


INTERNATIONAL 
CONGRESS   OF  ARTS  AND   SCIENCE 

UNIVERSAL  EXPOSITION   ST.   LOUIS 

SEPTEMBER  19-25  1904 


PROGRAMME  AND  LIST  OF  SPEAKERS 


PROGRAMME 


Purpose  and  Plan  of  the  Congress 

Organization  of  the  Congress 

Speakers  and  Chairmen 

Chronological  Order  of  Proceedings 

Programme  of  Social  Events 

List  of  Ten-minute  Speakers 

List  of  Chairmen  and  Principal  Speakers 


INDEX  SUBJECTS 
Division  A.  Normative  Science 


Department  i.  Philosophy 

Sec.  A.  Metaphysics 

B.  Philosophy  of  Religion 

C.  Logic 

D.  Methodology  of  Science 

E.  Ethics 

F.  Esthetics 


Department  2.  Mathematics 

Sec.  A.  Algebra  and  Anatysis 

B.  Geometry 

C.  Applied  Mathematics 


Division  B.  Historical  Science 


Department  3.  Political  and 
Economic  History 

Sec.  A.  History  of  Asia 

B.  History  of  Greece  and  Rome 

C.  Mediaeval  History 

D.  Modem  History  of  Europe 

E.  History  of  America 

F.  History  of  Economic  Institu- 

tions 

Department  4.  History  of  Law 

Sec.  A.  History  of  Roman  Law 

B.  History  of  Common  Law 

C.  Comparative  Law 

Department  5.  History  of 
Language 

Sec.  A.  Comparative  Language 

B.  Semitic  Language 

C.  Indo-Iranian  Languages 

D.  Greek  Language    • 

E.  Latin  Language 

F.  English  Language 

G.  Romance  Languages 
H.  Germanic  Languages 


Department  6.  History  of  Lit- 
erature 

Sec.  A.  Indo-Iranian  Literature 

B.  Classical  Literature 

C.  Enghsh  Literature 

D.  Romance  Literature 

E.  Germanic  Literature 

F.  Slavic  Literature 

G.  BeUes-Lettres 

Department  7.  History  of  Art 

Sec.  A.  Classical  Art 

B.  Modem  Architecture 

C.  Modem  Painting 

Department  8.  History  of  Re- 
ligion 

Sec.  A.  Brahminism  and  Buddhism 

B.  Mohammedism 

C.  Old  Testament 

D.  New  Testament 

E.  History  of  the  Christian 

Church 


48 


PROGRAMME 


Division  C.  Physical  Science 


Department  9.  Physics 

Sec.  A.  Physics  of  Matter 

B.  Physics  of  Ether 

C.  Physics  of  the  Electron 

Department  10.  Chemistry- 
Sec.  A.  Inorganic  Chemistry 

B.  Organic  Chemistry 

C.  Physical  Chemistry 

D.  Physiological  Chemistry 

Department  11.  Astronomy 

Sec.  A.  Astrometry 
B.  Astrophysics 

Department  12.  Sciences  of  the 
Earth 

Sec.  A.  Geophysics 

B.  Geology 

C.  Palaeontology 

D.  Petrology  and  Mineralogy 

E.  Physiography 

F.  Geography 

G.  Oceanography 
H.  Cosmical  Physics 


Department  13.  Biology 

Sec.  A.  Phylogeny 

B.  Plant  Morphology 

C.  Plant  Physiology 

D.  Plant  Pathology 

E.  Ecology 

F.  Bacteriology 

G.  Animal  Morphology 
H.  Embryology 

I.  Comparative  Anatomy 
J.  Human  Anatomy 
K.  Physiology 

Department  14.  Anthropology 

Sec.  A.  Somatology 

B.  Archaeology 

C.  Ethnology 


Division  D.  Mental  Science 


Department  15.  Psychology 

Sec.  A.  General  Psychology 

B.  Experimental  Psychology 

C.  Comparative    and    Genetic 

Psychology 

D.  Abnormal  Psychology 


Department  16.  Sociology 

Sec.  B.  Social  Structure 
C.  Social  Psychology 


Division  E.  Utilitarian  Sciences 


Department  17.  Medicine 

Sec.  A.  Pubhc  Health 

B.  Preventive  Medicine 

C.  Pathology 

D.  Therapeutics  and  Phar- 

macology 

E.  Internal  Medicine 

F.  Neurology 

G.  Psychiatry 
H.  Surgery 

I.  G5Tiecology 

J.  Ophthalmology 

K.  Otology  and  Laryngology 

L.  Pediatrics 


Department  18.  Technology 

Sec.  A.  Civil  Engineering 

B.  Mechanical  Engineering 

C.  Electrical  Engineering 

D.  Mining  Engineering 

E.  Technical  Chemistry 

F.  Agriculture 

Department  19.  Economics 

Sec.  A.  Economic  Theory 

B.  Transportation 

C.  Commerce  and  Exchange 

D.  Money  and  Credit 

E.  Public  Finance 

F.  Insurance 


PROGRAMME 


49 


Division  F. 
Department  20.  Politics 

Sec.  A.  Political  Theory 

B.  Diplomacy 

C.  National  Administration 

D.  Colonial  Administration 

E.  Municipal  Administration 

Department  21.  Jurisprudence 

Sec.  A.  International  Law 

B.  Constitutional  Law 

C.  Private  Law 


Social  Regulation 

Department  22.  Social  Science 

Sec.  A.  The  Family 

B.  The  Rural  Community 

C.  The  Urban  Commimity 

D.  The  Indu^rial  Group 

E.  The  Dependent  Group 

F.  The  Criminal  Group 


Division  G.  Social  Culture 


Department  23.  Education 

Sec.  A.  Educational  Theory 

B.  The  School 

C.  The  College 

D.  The  University 

E.  The  Library 


Department  24.  Religion 

Sec.  A.  General  Religious    Educa- 
tion 

B.  Professional  Rehgious  Edu- 

cation 

C.  Religious  Agencies 

D.  Religious  Work 

E.  Religious  Influence:  Per- 

sonal 

F.  Religious  Influence:  Social 


PURPOSE  AND   PLAN   OF  THE   CONGRESS 

The  idea  of  the  Congress  grows  out  of  the  thought  that  the  sub- 
division and  multiphcation  of  specialties  in  science  has  reached  a  stage 
at  which  investigators  and  scholars  may  derive  both  inspiration  and 
profit  from  a  general  survey  of  the  various  fields  of  learning,  planned 
with  a  view  of  bringing  the  scattered  sciences  into  closer  mutual 
relations.  The  central  purpose  is  the  unification  of  knowledge,  an 
effort  toward  which  seems  appropriate  on  an  occasion  when  the 
nations  bring  together  an  exhibit  of  their  arts  and  industries.  An 
assemblage  is  therefore  to  be  convened  at  which  leading  represent- 
atives of  theoretical  and  applied  sciences  shall  set  forth  those  general 
principles  and  fundamental  conceptions  which  connect  groups  of 
sciences,  review  the  historical  development  of  special  sciences,  show 
their  mutual  relations  and  discuss  their  present  problems. 

The  speakers  to  treat  the  various  themes  are  selected  in  advance 
from  the  European  and  American  continents.  The  discussions  will 
be  arranged  on  the  following  general  plan :  — 

After  the  opening  of  the  Congress  on  Monday  afternoon,  Septem- 
ber 19,  will  follow,  on  Tuesday  forenoon,  addresses  on  main  divisions 
of  science  and  its  applications,  the  general  theme  being  the  unification 
of  each  of  the  fields  treated.  These  will  be  followed  by  two  addresses 
on  each  of  the  twenty-four  great  departments  of  knowledge.  The 
theme  of  one  address  in  each  case  will  be  the  Fundamental  Concep- 
tions and  Methods,  while  the  other  will  set  forth  the  progress  during 
the  last  century.  The  preceding  addresses  will  be  delivered  by  Ameri- 
cans, making  the  work  of  the  first  two  days  the  contribution  of 
American  scholars. 

On  the  third  day,  with  the  opening  of  the  sections,  the  international 
work  will  begin.  One  hundred  twenty-eight  sectional  meetings  will 
be  held  on  the  four  remaining  days  of  the  Congress,  at  each  of 
which  two  papers  will  be  read,  the  theme  of  one  being  suggested  by 
the  relations  of  the  special  branch  treated  to  other  branches;  the 
other  by  its  present  problems.  Three  hours  will  be  devoted  to  each 
sectional  meeting,  thus  enabling  each  hearer  to  attend  eight  such 
meetings,  if  he  so  desires.  The  programme  is  so  arranged  that  related 
subjects  will  be  treated,  as  far  as  possible,  at  different  times.  The 
length  of  the  principal  addresses  being  limited  to  forty-five  minutes 
each,  there  will  remain  at  least  one  hour  for  five  or  six  brief  communi- 
cations in  each  section.  The  addresses  in  each  department  will  be 
collected  and  published  in  a  special  volume. 


PURPOSE  AND   PLAN  OF  THE  CONGRESS  51 

It  is  hoped  that  the  living  influence  of  this  meeting  will  be  yet  more 
important  than  the  formal  addresses,  and  that  the  scholars  whose 
names  are  announced  in  the  following  programme  of  speakers  and 
chairmen  will  form  only  a  nucleus  for  the  gathering  of  thousands  who 
feel  in  sympathy  with  the  efforts  to  bring  unity  into  the  world  of 
knowledge. 


ORGANIZATION  OF  THE   CONGRESS 


PRESIDENT  OF  THE  EXPOSITION: 
HON.  DAVID  R.  FRANCIS,  A.M.,  LL.D. 

DIRECTOR  OF  CONGRESSES, 

HOWARD  J.   ROGERS,   A.M.,   LL.D.. 

Universal  Exposition,  1904. 


ADMINISTRATIVE  BOARD 

NICHOLAS   MURRAY  BUTLER,  Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

President  of  Columbia  University,  Chairman. 

WILLIAM  R.   HARPER,  Ph.D.,   LL.D. 
President  of  the  University  of  Chicago. 

R.   H.   JESSE,   Ph.D.,   LL.D. 
President  of  the  University  of  Missouri. 

HENRY   S.    PRITCHETT,   Ph.D.,   LL.D. 
President  of  the  Massachusetts  Institute  of  Technology. 

HERBERT   PUTNAM,   Litt.D.,  LL.D. 
Librarian  of  Congress. 

FREDERICK  J.   V.   SKIFF,   A.M. 
Director  of  the  Field  Columbian  Museum. 


OFFICERS  OF  THE   CONGRESS 


PRESIDENT: 

SIMON   NEWCOMB,   Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

Retired  Processor  U.  S.  N. 

VICE-PRESIDENTS: 
HUGO   MtJNSTERBERG,  Ph.D.,  LL.D. 

Professor  of  Psychology  in  Harvard  University. 

ALBION  W.   SMALL,  Ph.D.,   LL.D. 

Professor  of  Sociology  in  The  University  of  Chicago. 

HONORARY  VICE-PRESIDENTS: 

RIGHT  HONORABLE  JAMES  BRYCE,  M.P. 

Great  Britain. 

M.   GASTON   DARBOUX, 

France. 

PROFESSOR  WILHELM  WALDEYER, 

Germany. 

DR.   OSKAR  BACKLUND, 

Russia. 

PROFESSOR  THEODORE  ESCHERICH, 

Austria, 

SIGNOR  ATTILIO  BRUNIALTI, 
Italy. 

PROFESSOR  N.  HOZUMI, 
Japan. 

EXECUTIVE  SECRETARY: 
DR.  L.  0.  HOWARD, 

Permanent  Secretary  American  Association 
for  the  Advancement  of  Science. 


SPEAKERS  AND    CHAIRMEN 


DIVISION  A— NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 

Speakek  :       Professor  Josiah  Royce,  Harvard  University. 
{Hall  6,  September  20,  10  a.  m.) 


Chairman  : 
Speakers  : 


SECTION  A. 

Chairman: 
Speakers: 

Secretary : 


DEPARTMENT   1  —  PHILOSOPHY 

(Hall  6,  September  20,  11.15  a.  m.) 

Professor  Borden  P.  Bowne,   Boston  University. 
Professor  George  H.  Howison,  University  of  Cali- 
fornia. 
Professor  George  T.  Ladd,  Yale  University. 

METAPHYSICS.    {Hall  6,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Professor  A.  C.  Armstrong,  Wesleyan  University. 
Professor  A.  E.  Taylor,  McGlII  University,  Montreal. 
Professor  Alexander  T.   Ormond,   Princeton  Uni- 
versity. 
Professor  A.  O.  Lovejoy,  Washington  University. 


SECTION  B.    PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION.    {Hall  1,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Thomas  C.  Hall,  Union  Theological  Sem- 
inary, N.  Y. 

Speakers:     Professor  Otto  Pfleiderer,  University  of  Berlin. 
Professor  Ernst  Troeltsch,  University  of  Heidel- 
berg. 

Secretary:   Dr.  W.  P.  Montague,  Columbia  University. 

SECTION  C.    LOGIC.    {Hall  6,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  George  M.  Duncan,  Yale  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  William  A.  Hammond,  Cornell  University. 
Professor  Frederick  J.  E.  Woodbridge,  Columbia 
University. 
Secretary:   Dr.  W.  H.  Sheldon,  Columbia  University. 

SECTION  D.    METHODOLOGY  OF  SCIENCE.   {Hall  6,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  James  E.  Creighton,  Cornell  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  Wilhelm  Ostwald,  University  of  Leipzig. 

Professor  Benno  Erdmann,  University  of  Bonn. 
Secretary:   Dr.  R.  B.  Perry,  Harvard  University. 


SECTION  E. 

Chairman: 
Speakers  : 


Secretary; 


ETHICS.     {Hall  6,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Professor  George  H.  Palmer,  Harvard  University. 
Professor  William  R.  Sorley,  University  of  Cam- 
bridge. 
Professor  Paul  Hensel,  University  of  Erlangen, 
Professor  F.  C.  Sharp,  University  of  Wisconsin. 


SPEAKERS   AND   CHAIRMEN 


55 


SECTION  F.  AESTHETICS.    {Hall  4,  September  23,  3  p.  to.) 
Chairman:     Professor  James  H.  Tufts,  University  of  Chicago. 
Speakers : 


Secretary: 

Chairman: 
Speakers: 

SECTION  A. 

Chairman  : 
Speakers: 

Secretary : 

SECTION  B. 

Chairman: 

Speakers: 

Secretary: 

SECTION  C. 

Chairman: 

Speakers: 
Secretary : 


Dr.  Henry  Rutgers  Marshall,  New  York  City. 
Professor  Max  Dessoir,  University  of  Berlin. 
Professor  Max  Meyer,  University  of  Missouri. 

DEPARTMENT  2  —  MATHEMATICS 

{Hall  7,  September  20,  11.15  a.  m.) 
Professor  Henry  S.  White,  Northwestern  Univers- 
ity. 
Professor  Maxime  B6cher,  Harvard  University. 
Professor  James  P.  Pierpont,  Yale  University. 

ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS.    {Hall  9,  September  22,  10  o.  to.) 

Professor  E.  H.  Moore,  University  of  Chicago. 
Professor  Emile  Pi  card,  The  Sorbonne;    Member 

of  the  Institute  of  France. 
Professor  Heinrich  Maschke,  University  of  Chicago. 
Professor  G.  A.  Bliss,  University  of  Chicago. 


GEOMETRY.    {Hall  9,  September  24,  10  a.  to.) 

Professor  M.  W.  Haskell,  University  of  California 
Darboux,    Perpetual    Secretary  of 


the 


M,   Gaston 

Academy  of  Sciences,  Paris. 

Dr.  Edward  Kasner,  Columbia  University. 

Professor  Thomas  J.  Holgate,  Northwestern  Uni- 
versity. 


{Hall  7,  September  24,  3  p.  to.) 
Webster,  Clark  University, 


APPLIED  MATHEMATICS. 

Professor  Arthur  G. 

Worcester,  Mass. 
Professor  Ludwig  Boltzmann,  University  of  Vienna. 
Professor  Henri  Poincare,  The  Sorbonne;  Member 

of  the  Institute  of  France. 
Professor  Henry  T.  Eddy,  University  of  Minnesota. 


DIVISION  B  — HISTORICAL  SCIENCE 

{Hall  3,  September  20,  10  a.  m.) 
Speaker:       President  Woodrow  Wilson,  Princeton  University. 


DEPARTMENT  3  —  POLITICAL  AND  ECONOMIC  HISTORY 

{Halt  4:,  September  20,  11.15  a.  to.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Professor  William  M.  Sloane,  Columbia  University. 
Professor  James  H.  Robinson,  Columbia  University. 


56 


SPEAKERS  AND   CHAIRMEN 


SECTIONS  A  AND  B.    HISTORY  OF  GREECE,  ROME.  AND  ASIA.    (.Hall  3, 
September  21,  10  a.  m.) 


Chairman: 

Speakers; 


Secretary: 


Professor  Thomas  D.  Seymour,  Yale  University. 

Professor  John  P.  Mahaffy,  University  of  Dublin, 

Professor  Ettore  Pais,  University  of  Naples.  Direc- 
tor of  the  National  Museum  of  Antiquities,  Naples. 

Professor  Henri  Cordier,  Ecole  des  Langues  Viv- 
antes  Orientales,  Paris. 

Professor  Edward  Capps,  University  of  Chicago. 


SECTION  C.    MEDIAEVAL  HISTORY.    {Hall  6,  September  21,  3  p.  to.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Charles  H.  Haskins,  Harvard  University. 
Speakers  :     Professor  Karl  Lamprecht,  University  of  Leipzig. 

Professor  George  B.  Adams,  Yale  University. 
Secretary:   Professor  Earle  W.  Dow,  University  of  Michigan. 


SECTION  D. 

Chairman  : 

Speakers: 


Secretary : 

SECTION  E. 

Chairman  : 
Speakers: 


Secretary 
SECTION  F. 


MODERN  HISTORY  OF  EUROPE.     {Hall  3,  September  22, 

10  a.  m.) 
Honorable  James  B.  Perkins,  Rochester,  N.  Y. 
Professor  J.  B.  Bury,  University  of  Cambridge. 
Professor   Charles  W.   Colby,   McGill  University, 

Montreal. 
Professor  Ferdinand  Schwill,  University  of  Chicago. 

HISTORY  OF  AMERICA.    {Hall  1,  September  24,  lO  a.  m.) 

Dr.  James  Schouler,  Boston. 

Professor  Frederic  J.  Turner,  University  of  Wis- 
consin. 
Professor  Edward  G.  Bourne,  Yale  University. 
Professor  Evarts  B.  Greene,  University  of  Illinois. 


{Hall  2,  Septem- 


HISTORY  OF  ECONOMIC  INSTITUTIONS. 

ber  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Frank  A.  Fetter,  Cornell  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  J.  E.  Conrad,  University  of  Halle. 

Professor  Simon  N.  Patten,   University    of   Penn- 
sylvania. 
Secretary:   Dr.  J.  Pease  Norton,  Yale  University. 

DEPARTMENT  4  — HISTORY  OF  LAW 
{Hall  5,  September  20,  11.15  a.  to.) 

Chairman:    Honorable  David  J.  Brewer,  Associate  Justice  of 
the  Supreme  Court  of  the  United  States. 

Speakers:     Honorable  Emlin  McClain,  Judge  of  the  Supreme 
Court  of  Iowa,  Iowa  City. 
Professor    Nathan   Abbott,  Leland    Stanford    Jr. 
University. 

SECTION  A.   HISTORY  OF  ROMAN  LAW.    {Hall  11,  September  21,  3  p.  to.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Mr.  W.  H.  Buckler,  Baltimore,  Md. 

Professor  Munroe  Smith,  Columbia  University. 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


57 


SECTION  B.    HISTORY  OF  COMMON  LAW.  (,Hall  11,  September  21, 10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  John  D.  Lawson,  University  of  Missouri. 
Speakers  :     Honorable  Simeon  E,  Baldwin,  Judge  of  the  Supreme 
Court  of  Errors,  New  Haven,  Conn. 
Professor    John    H.  Wigmore,  Northwestern   Uni- 
versity. 
Secretary:   Professor  C.  H.  Huberich,  University  of  Texas. 

SECTION  C.    COMPARATIVE  LAW.    {Hall  14,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Honorable  Jacob  M.  Dickinson,  Chicago. 
Speakers:     Professor  Nobushige  Hozumi,  TJniversity  of  Tokio. 
Professor  Alfred  Nerincx,  University  of  Louvain. 
Secretary: 

DEPARTMENT  5  — HISTORY  OF  LANGUAGE 
{Hall  4,  September  20,  2  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  George  Hempl,  University  of  Michigan, 
Speakers:     Professor  T.  R,  Lounsbury,  Yale  University. 

President  Benjamin  Ide  Wheeler,  University  of 
California. 

SECTION  A.    COMPARATIVE  LANGUAGE.  (Hall  4,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Francis  A.  March,  Lafayette  College. 
Speakers:     Professor  Carl  D.  Buck,  University  of  Chicago. 

Professor  Hans  Oertel,  Yale  University. 
Secretary:   Professor  E.  W.  Fay,  University  of  Texas,  Austin, 
Texas. 

SECTION  B.    SEMITIC  LANGUAGES.    {Hall  4,  September' 21,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  G.  F.  Moore,  Harvard  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  James  A.  Craig,  University  of  Michigan. 

Professor  Crawford  H.  Toy,  Harvard  University. 
Secretary: 

SECTION  C.   INDO-IRANLAJ?  LANGUAGES.  {Hall  8,  September  22, 10  a.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Professor  Sylvain  Levi,  College  de  France,  Paris. 

Professor   Arthur   A,    Macdonell,   University    of 
Oxford. 
Secretary : 

SECTION  D.    GREEK  LANGUAGE.    (Hall  3,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) ' 

Chairman  :     Professor  Martin  L.  D'Ooge,  University  of  Michigan. 
Speakers:     Professor  Herbert  W.  Smyth,  Harvard  University. 
Professor   Milton   W.   Humphreys,   University   of 
Virginia. 
Secretary:   Professor  J.  E.  Harry,  University  of  Cincinnati. 

SECTION  E.    LATIN  LANGUAGE.    (Hall  9,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 
Chairman:     Professor  Maurice  Hutton,  University  of  Toronto. 
Speakers:     Professor  E.  A.  Sonnenschein,  University  of  Bir- 
mingham. 
Professor  William  G.  Hale,  University  of  Chicago. 
Secretary:   Professor  F.  W.  Shipley,  Washington  University. 


58  SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 

SECTION  F.    ENGLISH  LANGUAGE.    {Hall  3,  September  23,  3  p.  to.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Charles  M.  Gayley,  University  of  Cal- 
ifornia. 

Speakers:     Professor   Otto   Jespersen,  University   of   Copen- 
hagen. 
Professor  George  L.  Kittredge,  Harvard  University. 

Secretary : 

SECTION  G.    ROMANCE  LANGUAGES.    {Hall  5,  September  24,  10  a.  to.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Professor  Paul  Meyer,  College  de  France,  Paris. 
Professor  Henry  A.  Todd,  Columbia  University. 
Secretary:   Professor  E.  E.  Brandon,  Miami  University. 

SECTION  H.    GERMANIC  LANGUAGES.    {Hall  3,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Gustaf  E.  Karsten,  Cornell  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  Eduard  Sievers,  University  of  Leipzig, 

Professor  Herman  Collitz,  Bryn  Mawr  College. 
Secretary : 

DEPARTMENT  6  — HISTORY  OF   LITERATURE 

{Hall  6,  September  20,  4.15  p.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers  :     Professor  James  A.  Harrison,  University  of  Virginia. 
Professor  Charles  M.  Gayley,  University  of  Cali- 
fornia. 

SECTION  A.    IltoO-IRANDm  LITERATURE.  {Hall  8,  September  24,  3  p.  to.) 

Chairman:     Professor    Maurice    Bloomfield,    Johns    Hopkins 

University. 
Speaker:       Professor  A.  V.  W.  Jackson,  Columbia  University. 
Secretary : 

SECTION  B.    CLASSICAL  LITERATURE.    {Hall  3,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Andrew  F.  West,  Princeton  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  Paul  Shorey,  University  of  Chicago. 

Professor  John  H.  Wright,  Harvard  University. 
Secretary:   Professor  F.  G.  Moore,  Dartmouth  College. 

SECTION  C.    ENGLISH  LITERATURE.    {Hall  1,  September  22,  10  a.  to.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Professor  Francis  B.  Gummere,  Haverford  College. 

Professor  John  Hoops,  University  of  Heidelberg. 
Secretary : 

SECTION  D.    ROMANCE  LITERATURE.    {Hall  8,  September  22,  3  p.  to.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Adolphe  Cohn,  Columbia  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  Pio  Rajna,  Institute  of  Higher  Studies, 

Florence,  Italy. 
Professor  Alc^e  Fortier,  Tulane  University,  New 

Orleans. 
Secretary:   Dr.  Comfort,  Haverford  College. 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


59 


SECTION  E. 

Chairman: 
Speakers: 

Secretary : 
SECTION  F. 

Chair]V[an: 
Speakers: 

Secretary : 
SECTION  G. 

Chairman: 
Speakers: 


GERMANIC  LITERATURE.    {Hall  3,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Professor  Kuno  Francke,  Harvard  University. 
Professor  August  Sauer,  University  of  Prague. 
Professor  J.  Minor,  University  of  Vienna. 
Professor  D.  K.  Jessen,  Bryn  Mawr  College. 


Secretary: 


Chairman: 
Speakers  : 


SECTION  A. 

Chairman: 
Speakers  : 

Secretary 
SECTION  B. 

Chairman: 
Speakers  : 

Secretary : 
SECTION  C. 

Chairman: 
Speakers: 

Secretary: 


SLAVIC  LITERATURE.    {Hall  8,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Mr.  Charles  R.  Crane,  Chicago. 
Professor  Leo  Wiener,  Harvard  University. 
Professor  Paul  Boyer,  Ecole  des  Langues  Vivantes 

Orientales,  Paris. 
Mr.  S.  N.  Harper,  University  of  Chicago. 

BELLES-LETTRES.    {Hall  3,  September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Professor  Robert  Herrick,  University  of  Chicago. 
Professor  Henry  Schofield,  Harvard  University. 
Professor  Brander  Matthews,  Columbia   Univers- 
ity. 

DEPARTMENT  7  —  HISTORY  OF  ART 
{Hall  8,  September  20,  11.15  a.  m.) 

Professor  Halsey  C.  Ives,  Washington  University, 

St.  Louis. 
Professor  Rufus  B.  Richardson,  New  York,  N.  Y. 
Professor  John  C.  Van  Dyke,  Rutgers  College. 

CLASSICAL    ART.    {Hall  12,  September  22,  10  a.  to.) 

Professor  Rufus  B.  Richardson,  New  York  City. 
Professor    Adolph    Furtwangler,    University    of 

Munich. 
Professor  Frank  B.  Tarbell,  University  of  Chicago. 
:   Dr.  p.  Baur,  Yale  University. 

MODERN  ARCHITECTURE.    {Hall  7,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Mr.  Charles  F.  McKim,  New  York  City. 
Professor  C.  Enlart,  University  of  Paris. 
Professor   Alfred   D.  F.   Hamlin,  Columbia   Uni- 
versity. 
Mr.  Guy  Lowell,  Boston,  Mass. 

MODERN  PAINTING.    {Hall  4,  September  24,  3  p.  to.) 

Professor  Richard  Muther,  University  of  Breslau. 
Mr.  Okakura  Kakuzo,  Japan. 


DEPARTMENT  8  — HISTORY  OF  RELIGION 

{Hall  5,  September  20,  2  p.  to.) 

Chairman:     Rev.  Wm.  Eliot  Griffis,  Ithaca,  N.  Y. 
Speakers:     Professor  George  F.  Moore,  Harvard  University. 
Professor  Nathaniel  Schmidt,  Cornell  University. 


60 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


SECTION  A.    BRAHMANISM  AND  BUDDHISM. 

10  a.  m.) 

Chairman: 
Speakers  : 


{Hall   8,    September    23, 


Professor  Hermann  Oldenberg,  University  of  Kiel. 
Professor    Maurice    Bloomfield,    Johns    Hopkins 
University. 
Secretary:  Dr.  Reginald  C.  Robbins,  Harvard  University. 

SECTION  B.    MOHAMMEDISM.    {Hall  8,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  James  R.  Jewett,  University  of  Chicago. 
Speakers:     Professor  Ignaz  Goldziher,  University  of  Budapest. 
Professor  Duncan  B.  Macdonald,  Hartford  Theo- 
logical Seminary. 
Secretary: 

SECTION  C.    OLD  TESTAMENT.    {Hall  4,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor   A.   S.    Carrier,   McCormick   Theological 

Seminary. 
Speakers:     Professor  James  F.  McCurdy,  University  College  of 

Toronto. 
Professor  Karl  Budde,  University  of  Marburg. 
Secretary:   Professor   James   A.    Kelso,   Western   Theological 

Seminary,  Allegheny,  Pa. 

SECTION  D.    NEW  TESTAMENT.    {Hall  1,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Andrew  C.  Zenos,  McCormick  Theological 

Seminary. 
Speakers:     Professor  Benjamin  W.  Bacon,  Yale  University. 

Professor  Ernest  D.  Burton,  University  of  Chicago. 
Secretary:   Professor  Clyde  W.  Votaw,  University  of  Chicago. 

SECTION  E.    HISTORY  OF  THE  CHRISTIAN  CHURCH.      {Hall  2,   Sep- 
tember 24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  Eri  Baker  Hulbert,  University  of  Chicago. 
Speakers:     Professor  Adolf  Harnack,  University  of  Berlin. 
Professor    Jean    Reville,   Faculty   of   Protestant 
Theology,  Paris. 
Secretary : 


DIVISION  C  — PHYSICAL  SCIENCE 

{Hall  4,  September  20,  10  a.  m.) 
Speaker:  Professor  Robert  S.  Woodward,  Columbia  University. 


DEPARTMENT  9  —  PHYSICS 

{Hall  6,  September  20,  2  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Henry  Crew,  Northwestern  University. 
Speakers:      Professor  Edward  L.  Nichols,  Cornell  University. 
Professor  Carl  Barus,  Brown  University. 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


61 


SECTION  A.    PHYSICS  OF  MATTER.    (Hall  11,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:  Professor  Samuel  W.  Stratton,  Director  of  the 
National  Bureau  of  Standards,  Washington. 

Speakers:    Professor  Arthur  L.  Kimball,  Amherst  College. 

Professor  Francis   E.   Nipher,    Washington    Uni- 
versity. 

Secretary:   Professor  R.  A.  Milliken,  University  of  Chicago. 

SECTION  B.    PHYSICS  OF  ETHER.    (Hall  11,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:    Professor  Henry  Crew,  Northwestern  University. 

Speaker:  Professor  DeWitt  B.  Brace,  University  of  Ne- 
braska. 

Secretary:  Professor  Augustus  Trowbridge,  University  of 
Wisconsin. 

SECTION  C.    PHYSICS  OF  THE  ELECTRON.  {Hall  5,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  A.  G.  Webster,  Clark  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  P.  Langevin,  College  de  France. 

Professor  Ernest  Rutherfurd,  McGill  University, 
Montreal. 
Secretary:  Professor  W.  J.  Humphreys,  University  of  Virginia. 


.    DEPARTMENT   10  — CHEMISTRY 
{Hall  5,  September  20,  4.15  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  James  M.  Crafts,  Massachusetts  Institute 

of  Technology. 
Speakers:     Professor  John  U.  Nef,  University  of  Chicago. 

Professor  Frank  W.  Clarke,  Chief  Chemist,  U.  S. 

Geological  Survey. 

SECTION  A.    INORGANIC  CHEMISTRY.    {Hall  16,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  John  W.  Mallet,  University  of  Virginia. 

Speakers:     Professor  Henri  Moissan,  The  Sorbonne;   Member 
of  the  Institute  of  France. 
Sir  William    Ramsay,   K.C.B.,  Royal     Institution, 
London. 

Secretary:  Professor  William  L.  Dudley,  Vanderbilt  Univers- 
ity. 

SECTION  B.    ORGANIC  CHEMISTRY.    {Hall  16,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Albert  B.  Prescott,  University  of  Michi- 
gan. 
Speakers:     Professor  Julius  Stieglitz,  University  of  Chicago. 
Professor  William  A.  Noyes,  National  Bureau  of 
Standards. 
Secretary : 

SECTION  C.    PHYSICAL  CHEMISTRY.    {Hall  16,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Wilder  D.  Bancroft,  Cornell  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  J.  H.  Van  t'Hoff,  University  of   Berlin. 
Professor  Arthur  A.  Noyes,  Massachusetts  Institute 
of  Technology. 
Secretary:  Mr.  W.  R.  Whitney,  Schenectady,  N.  Y. 


62 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


SECTION  D.    PHYSIOLOGICAL  CHEMISTRY.    {Hall    16,    September    22, 
3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Wilbur  O.  At  water,  Wesleyan  Univers- 
ity. 
Speakers:     Professor  0.  Cohnheim,  University  of  Heidelberg. 
Professor  Russell  H.  Chittenden,  Yale  Univers- 
ity. 
Secretary:  Dr.  C.  L.  Alsberg,  Harvard  University. 


DEPARTMENT   11— ASTRONOMY 

{Hall  8,  September  20,  4.15  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor   George   C.    Comstock,  Director  of  the 
Observatory,  Madison,  Wisconsin. 

Speakers:     Professor  Lewis  Boss,  Director  of  Dudley  Observa- 
tory. 
Professor  Edward  C.  Pickering,  Director  of  Har- 
vard Observatory. 

SECTION  A.    ASTROMETRY.    {Hall  9,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Professor  Ormond  Stone,  University  of  Virginia. 


Chairman: 
Speakers : 


Secretary: 

SECTION  B. 

Chairman: 

Speakers  : 


Secretary: 


Dr.  Oskar  Backlund,  Director  of  the  Observatory, 
Pulkowa,  Russia. 

Professor  John  C.  Kapteyn,  University  of  Gronin- 
gen,  Holland. 

Professor  W.  S.  Eichelberger,  U.  S.  Naval  Observ- 
atory. 

ASTROPHYSICS.    {Hall  9,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 

Professor  George  E.  Hale,  Director  of  the  Yerkes 
Observatory. 

Professor  Herbert  H.  Turner,  F.R.S.,  Univers- 
ity of  Oxford. 

Professor  William  W.  Campbell,  Director  of  the 
Lick  Observatory,  Mt.  Hamilton,  California. 

Mr.  W.  S.  Adams,  Yerkes  Observatory. 


DEPARTMENT   12  — SCIENCES  OF   THE  EARTH 

{Hall  3,  September  20,  11.15  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  G.  K.  Gilbert,  U.  S.  Geological  Survey. 
Speakers:     Professor   Thomas   C.   Chamberlin,   University   of 
Chicago. 
Professor  William  M.  Davis,  Harvard  University. 

SECTION  A.    GEOPHYSICS.    {Hall  14,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor   Christopher   W.    Hall,    University   of 

Minnesota. 
Speaker:       Dr.  George  F.  Becker,  Geologist,  U.  S.  Geological 

Survey. 
Secretary:   Professor  E.  M.  Lehnerts,  Minnesota  State  Normal 

School. 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


63 


SECTION  B. 

Chairman: 

Speakers: 

Secretary : 
SECTION  C. 

Chairman: 

Speakers  : 

Secretary  : 
SECTION  D. 

Chairman: 

Speaker: 
Secretary : 

SECTION  E. 

Chairman: 
Speakers  : 

Secretary : 
SECTION  F. 

Chairman  : 
Speakers  : 

Secretary: 
SECTION  G. 

Chairman  : 

Speakers  : 

Secretary  : 
SECTION  H. 

Chairman  : 
Speakers: 


Secretary : 


GEOLOGY.    {Hall  14,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 

Professor  T.  C.  Chamberlin,  University  of  Chicago. 
President  Charles  R.  Van  Hise,  University  of  Wis- 
consin. 

Professor  R.  D.  Salisbury,  University  of  Chicago. 

PALAEONTOLOGY.    {Hall  11,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Professor  William  B.  Scott,  Princeton  University. 
Dr.  a.   S.  Woodward,   F.R.S.,   British   Museum   of 

Natural  History,  London. 
Professor  Henry  F.  Osborn,  Columbia  University. 
Dr.  John  M.  Clarke,  Albany,  N.  Y. 

PETROLOGY  AND  MINERALOGY.     {Hall  9,  September  22, 
3  p.  m.) 

Dr.  Oliver  C.  Farrington,  Field  Columbian  Museum, 

Chicago. 
Professor  F.  Zirkel,  University  of  Leipzig. 

PHYSIOGRAPHY.    {Hall  12,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Mr.  Henry  Gannett,  United  States  Geological  Survey. 
Professor  Albrecht  Penck,  University  of  Vienna. 
Professor  Israel  C.  Russell,  University  of  Michigan. 
Dr.  John  M.  Clarke,  Albany,  N.  Y. 

GEOGRAPHY.    {Hall  11,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Professor  Israel  C.  Russell,  University  of  Michigan. 
Dr.  Hugh  R.  Mill,  Director  British  Rainfall  Organ- 
ization, London. 
Professor  H.  Yule  Oldham,  Cambridge,  England. 
Professor  R.  D.  Salisbury,  University  of  Chicago. 

OCEANOGRAPHY.    {Hall  8,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 

Rear-Admiral   John   R.    Bartlett,   United   States 

Navy. 
Sir  John  Murray,  K.C.B.,  F.R.S.,  Edinburgh. 
Professor  K.  Mitsukuri,  University  of  Tokio. 

COSMICAL  PHYSICS.    {Hall  10,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Professor  Francis  E.  NiPHER,Washington  University. 
Professor  Svante  Arrhenius,  University  of  Stock- 
holm, Stockholm. 
Dr.  Abbott  L.  Rotch,  Blue  Hill  Observatory. 
Dr.  L.  a.  Bauer,  Washington,  D.  C. 


DEPARTMENT   13  —  BIOLOGY 

{Hall  "2,  September  20,  11.15  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  William  G.  Farlow,  Harvard  University. 

Speakers:     Professor  John  M.  Coulter,  IJniversity  of  Chicago. 

Professor  Jacques  Loeb,  University   of  California. 


64 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


SECTION  A.    PHYLOGENY.    {Hall  2,  September  21,  3  p.  to.) 


Chairman: 
Speakers: 


Secretary: 


Professor  T.  H.  Morgan,  Columbia  University. 
Professor  Hugo  de  Vries,  University  of  Amsterdam. 
Professor    Charles    0.    Whitman,    University    of 
Chicago. 


SECTION  B.    PLANT  MORPHOLOGY.    {Hall  2,  September  22,  10  a.  to.) 

Chairman:     Professor  William  Trelease,  Washington  Univers- 
ity, St.  Louis. 

Speakers:     Professor  Frederick  O.  Bower,  University  of  Glas- 
gow. 
Professor  Karl  F.  Goebel,  University  of  Munich. 

Secretary:   Professor  F.  E.  Lloyd,  Columbia  University. 

SECTION  C.    PLANT  PHYSIOLOGY.    {Hall  4,  September  22,  3  p.  to.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Charles  R.  Barnes,  University  of  Chicago. 
Speakers:     Professor  Julius  Wiesner,  University  of  Vienna. 
Professor  Benjamin  M.  Duggar,  University  of  Mis- 
souri. 
Secretary:   Professor  F.  C.  Newcomb,  University  of  Michigan. 

SECTION  D.     PLANT  PATHOLOGY.    {Hall  7,  September  23,  10  a.  to.) 

Chairman:    Professor  Chas.  E.  Bessey,  University  of  Nebraska. 
Speakers  :     Professor  Joseph  C.  Arthur,  Purdue  University. 

Merton  B.  Waite,  U.  S.  Department  of  Agriculture. 
Secretary:   Dr.  C.  S.  Shear,  U.  S.  Department  of  Agriculture. 


SECTION  E.    ECOLOGY.    {Hall  7,  September  23,  3  p.  to.) 

Chairman: 
Speakers: 


Secretary : 


Professor   Oskar   Drude,   Kon.   Technische  Hoch- 

schule,  Dresden. 
Professor  Benjamin  Robinson,  Harvard  University. 
Professor  F.  E.  Clements,  University  of  Nebraska. 


SECTION  F.    BACTERIOLOGY.    {Hall  15,  September  24,  10  a.  to.) 

Professor  Harold  C.  Ernst,    Harvard   University. 


Chairman: 
Speakers  : 

Secretary : 


Professor  Edwin  O.  Jordan,  University  of  Chicago. 
Professor  Theobald  Smith,  Harvard  University. 
Dr.  p.  H.  Hiss,  Jr.,  Columbia  University. 


SECTION  G. 

Chairman: 

Speakers  : 


Secretary  : 


ANIMAL  MORPHOLOGY.    {Hall  2,  September  21,  10  a.  to.) 

Dr.  Leland  0.  Howard,  Department  of  Agriculture, 

Washington,  D.  C. 
Professor   Charles   B.    Davenport,  University   of 

Chicago. 
Professor  Alfred  Giard,  The  Sorbonne;    Member 

of  the  Institute  of  France. 
Professor  C.  H.  Herrick,  Dennison  University. 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


65 


SECTION  H.    EMBRYOLOGY.    {Hall  9,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Simon  H.  Gage,  Cornell  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  Oskar  Hertwig,  University  of  Berlin, 

Professor    William    K.    Brooks,    Johns    Hopkins 
University. 
Secretary:   Professor  T.  G.  Lee,  University  of  Minnesota. 

SECTION  I.    COMPARATIVE  ANATOMY.    {Hall  2,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor    James    P.    McMurrich,    University    of 
Michigan. 

Speakers:     Professor  William  E.  Ritter,  University  of  Cali- 
fornia. 
Professor  Yves  Delage,  The  Sorbonne ;  Member  of 
the  Institute  of  France. 

Secretary:   Professor  Henry  B.  Ward,  University  of  Nebraska. 

SECTION  J.    HUMAN  ANATOMY.    {Hall  2,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  George  A.  Piersol,  University  of  Penn- 
sylvania. 
Speakers:     Professor  Wilhelm  Waldeyer,  University  of  Berlin. 
Professor  H.  H.  Donaldson,  University  of  Chicago. 
Secretary:   Dr.  R.  J.  Terry,  Washington  University. 

SECTION  K.    PHYSIOLOGY.    {Hall  4,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  S.  J.  Meltzer,  New  York. 

Speakers:     Professor  Max  Verworn,  University  of  Gottingen. 
Professor  William  H.  Howell,  Johns  Hopkins  Uni- 
versity. 
Secretary:   Dr.  Reid  Hunt,  Washington. 

DEPARTMENT   14  —  ANTHROPOLOGY 

{Hall  8,  September  20,  2  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Frederic  W.  Putnam,  Harvard  Univers- 
ity. 

Speakers:     Dr.  WJ  McGee,  President  American  Anthropological 
Association,  Washington,  D.  C. 
Professor  Franz  Boas,  Columbia  University. 

SECTION  A.    SOMATOLOGY.    {Hall  16,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  Edward  C.  Spitzka,  New  York  City. 
Speakers:     Professor  L.  Manouvrier,  School  of  Anthropology^ 

Paris. 
Dr.  George  A.  Dorsey,  Field  Columbian   Museum^. 

Chicago. 
Secretary:  Dr.  E.  A.  Spitzka,  New  York  City. 

SECTION  B.    ARCHAEOLOGY.    {Hall  16,  September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Mr.  M.  H.   Saville,  American  Museum  of  Natural 

History,"  New  York. 
Speakers:     Senor  Alfredo  Chavero,  Inspector  of  the  National 

Museum,  Mexico. 
Professor  Edouard  Seler,  University  of  Berlin. 
Secretary:   Professor  William  C.  Mills,  Ohio  State  University. 


66 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


SECTION  C.    ETHNOLOGY.    {Hall  16,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Miss  Alice  C.  Fletcher,  President  of  the  Washing- 
ton Anthropological  Society. 
Speakers:     Professor  Frederick  Starr,  University  of  Chicago. 
Professor  A.  C.  Haddon,  University  of  Cambridge. 
Secretary:   Professor  F.  W.  Shipley,  Washington  University. 


Speaker: 


DIVISION   D.  — MENTAL   SCIENCE 

{Hall  7,  September  20,  10  a.  m.) 

President  G.  Stanley  Hall,  Clark  University,  Wor- 
cester, Mass. 


DEPARTMENT  15  —  PSYCHOLOGY 

{Hall  7,  September  20,  2  p.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers  :     Professor  James  McK.  Cattell,  Columbia  University. 
Professor  J.  Mark  Baldwin,  Johns  Hopkins  Uni- 
versity. 

SECTION  A.    GENERAL  PSYCHOLOGY.    {Hall  6,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Jos.  Royce,  Harvard  University. 

Speakers:     Professor  Harald  Hoeffding,  University  of  Copen- 
hagen. 
Professor  James  Ward,  University  of  Cambridge, 
England. 

Secretary:   Dr.  W.  H.  Davis,  Lehigh  University. 

SECTION  B.    EXPERIMENTAL,  PSYCHOLOGY.      {Hall   2,   September   23, 
10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Edward  A.  Pace,  Catholic  University  of 

America. 
Speakers  :     Professor  Robert  MacDougal,  New  York  University. 
Professor  Edward  B.  Titchener,  Cornell  University. 
Secretary:   Dr.  R.  S.  Wood  worth,  Columbia  University. 

SECTION   C.     COMPARATIVE  AND  GENETIC  PSYCHOLOGY.     {Hall  6, 
September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor   Edmund   C.    Sanford,  Clark  University, 

Worcester,  Mass. 
Speakers:     Principal   C.    Lloyd    Morgan,   University   College, 
Bristol. 
Professor  Mary  W.  Calkins,  Wellesley  College. 
Secretary:   Dr.  R.  M.  Yerkes,  Harvard  University. 

SECTION  D.    ABNORMAL  PSYCHOLOGY.    {Hall  6,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  Edward  Cowles,  Waverley,  Mass. 

Speakers:     Dr.  Pierre  Janet,  College  de  France,  Paris. 

Dr.  Morton  Prince,  Boston. 

Secretary:   Dr.  Adolph  Meyer,  New  York  City. 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 
DEPARTMENT   16  —  SOCIOLOGY 


67 


Chaieman: 


{Hall  7,  September  20,  4.15  p.  m.) 
Professor  Frank  W.  Blackmar,  University  of  Kan- 


sas. 


Speakers:     Professor  Franklin  H.  Giddings,   Columbia   Uni- 
versity. 
Professor  George  E.  Vincent,  University  of  Chicago. 

SECTION  A.    SOCIAL  STRUCTURE.    {Hall  15,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Frederick  W.  Moore,  Vanderbilt   Uni- 
versity. 
Speakers:     Field  Marshal  Gustav  Ratzenhofer,  Vienna. 

Professor  F.  Toennies,  University  of  Kiel. 

Professor  Lester  F.  Ward,  U.  S.  National  Museum. 
Secretary:  Professor  Jerome  Dowd,  University  of  Wisconsin. 

SECTION  B.    SOCIAL  PSYCHOLOGY.    {Hall  15,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Charles  A.  Ell  wood.  University  of  Mis- 
souri. 


Speakers: 

Secretary:  Professor  E.  C.  Hayes,  Miami  University 


Professor  Wm.  I.  Thomas,  University  of  Chicago. 
Professor  Edward  A.  Ross,  University  of  Nebraska. 


Speaker: 


DIVISION  E— UTILITARIAN  SCIENCES 

{Hall  1,  September  20,  10  a.  m.) 

President  David  Starr  Jordan,  Leland  Stanford  Jr. 
University. 


DEPARTMENT   17  — MEDICINE 
{Hall  1,  September  20,  4,15  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  William  Osler,  Johns  Hopkins  University. 
Speakers:     Dr.  William  T.  Councilman,  Harvard  University. 
Dr.  Frank  Billings,  University  of  Chicago. 

SECTION  A.    PUBLIC  HEALTH.    {Hall  13,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  Walter  Wyman,  Surgeon-General  of  the  U.  S. 

Marine  Hospital  Service. 
Speakers:     Professor    William    T.    Sedgwick,    Massachusetts 

Institute  of  Technology. 
Dr.    Ernst  J.   Lederle,   Former    Commissioner    of 

Health,  New  York  City. 
Secretary:  Dr.  H.  .M  Bracken,  St.  Paul,  Minn. 


68  SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 

SECTION  B.    PREVENTIVE  MEDICINE.    {Hall  13,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  Joseph  M.  Mathews,  President  of  the  State  Board 

of  Health,  Louisville,  Ky. 
Speaker:       Professor  Ronald  Ross,  F.R.S.,  School  of  Tropical 

Medicine,  University  College,  Liverpool. 
Secretary:   Dr.  J.  N.  Hurty,  Indianapolis,  Ind. 

SECTION  C.    PATHOLOGY.    {Hall  13,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Simon  Flexner,  Director  of  the  Rocke- 
feller Institute. 
Speakers:     Professor  Ludwig  Hektoen,  University  of  Chicago. 
Professor  Johannes  Orth,  University  of  Berlin, 
Professor    Shibasaburo    Kitasato,    University    of 
Tokio. 
Secretary:   Dr.  W.  McN.  Miller,  University  of  Missouri. 

SECTION  D.    THERAPEUTICS  AND  PHARMACOLOGY.      {Hall  13,   Sep- 
tember 24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  Hobart  A.  Hare,  Jefferson  Medical  College. 
Speakers:      Professor  Oscar  Liebreich,  University  of  Berlin. 

Sir  Lauder  Brunton,  F.R.S.,  London. 
Secretary:   Dr.  H.  B.  Favill,  Chicago,  111. 

SECTION  E.    INTERNAL  MEDICINE.    {Hall  13,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Frederick  C.  Shattuck,    Harvard   Uni- 
versity. 

Speakers:     Professor  T.  Clifford  Allbutt,  F.R.S. ,  University 
of  Cambridge. 
Professor  William  S.  Thayer,  Johns  Hopkins  Uni- 
versity. 

Secretary:   Dr.  R.  C.  Cabot,  Boston,  Mass. 

SECTION  F.    NEUROLOGY.    {Hall  13,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor    Lewellyn    F.    Barker,    University    of 

Chicago. 
Speaker:       Professor  James  J.  Putnam,  Harvard  University. 
Secretary : 

SECTION  G.    PSYCHLATRY.     {Hall  7,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Dr.  Charles  L.  Dana,  Cornell  University,  New  York. 

Dr.  Edward  Cowles,  Boston. 
Secretary:   Dr.  C.  G.  Chaddock,  St.  Louis,  Mo. 

SECTION  H.    SURGERY.    {Hall  13,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Carl  Beck,  Post-Graduate  Medical  School, 

New  York. 
Speakers:     Dr.   Frederic  S.  Dennis,  F.R.C.S.,  Cornell  Medical 

College,  New  York  City. 
Professor  Johannes  Orth,  University  of  Berlin. 
Secretary:   Dr.  J.  F.  Binnie,  Kansas  City,  Mo. 


SPEAKERS  AND   CHAIRMEN  69 

SECTION  I.    GYNECOLOGY.    {Hall  13,  September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:  Professor  Howard  A.  Kelly,  Johns  Hopkins  Uni- 
versity. 

Speaker:  Professor  J.  Clarence  Webster,  Rush  Medical  Col- 
lege, Chicago. 

Secretary:   Dr.  G.  H.  Noble,  Atlanta,  Ga. 

SECTION  J.    OPHTHALMOLOGY.    (Hall  7,  September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  George  C.  Harlan,  Philadelphia,  Pa. 
Speakers:     Dr.  Edward  Jackson,  Denver,  Col. 

Dr.  George  M.  Gould,  Philadelphia,  Pa. 
Secretary:   Dr.  Wm.  M.  Sweet,  Jefferson  Medical  College,  Phil- 
adelphia, Pa. 

SECTION  K.  OTOLOGY  AND  LARYNGOLOGY.  (Hall  7,  September  21, 
10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:  Professor  William  C.  Glasgow,  Washington  Uni- 
versity, St.  Louis. 

Speaker:  Sir  Felix  Semon,  C.V.O.,  Physician  Extraordinary 
to  His  Majesty,  the  King,  London. 

Secretary:   Dr.  S.  Spencer,  Allenhurst,  N.  J. 

SECTION  L.    PEDIA.TRICS.    {Hall  7,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Thomas  M.  Rotch,  Harvard  University. 
Speakers  :     Professor  Theodore  Escherich,  University  of  Vienna. 

Professor  Abraham  Jacobi,  Columbia  University. 
Secretary:   Dr.  Samuel  S.  Adams,  Washington,  D.  C. 

DEPARTMENT  18  —  TECHNOLOGY. 

{Hall  3,  September  20,  2  p.  m.) 

Chairman:  Chancellor  Winfield  S.  Chaplin,  Washington  Uni- 
versity, St.  Louis. 

Speaker:  Professor  Henry  T.  Bovey,  F.R.S.,  McGill  Uni- 
versity, Montreal. 

SECTION  A.    CIVIL  ENGINEERING.    {Hall  10,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  William  H.  Burr,  Columbia  University. 

Speakers:     Dr.  J.  A.  L.  Waddell,  Consulting  Engineer,  Kansas 
City. 
Mr.   Lewis  M.   Haupt,  Consulting   Engineer,    Phila- 
delphia. 

Secretary : 

SECTION  B.  MECHANICAL  ENGINEERING.  {Hall  10,  September  23, 
3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  James  E.  Denton,  Stevens  Institute  of 

Technology. 
Speaker:       Professor  Albert   W.  Smith,  Leland  Stanford  Jr. 

University. 
Secretary:  Mr.  George  Dinkel,  Jr.,  Jersey  City. 


70  SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 

SECTION  C.    ELECTRICAL  ENGINEERING.        {Hall    10,    September    22, 
3  p.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Professor  Arthur  E.  Kennelly,  Harvard  Univers- 
ity. 
Professor  Michael  I.  Pupin,  Columbia  University. 
Secretary:   Mr.  Carl  Hering,  Philadelphia,  Pa. 

SECTION  D.    MINING  ENGINEERING.     {Hall  11,  September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Mr.  John  Hays  Hammond,  New  York  City. 

Speakers:     Professor    Robert    H.    Richards,     Massachusetts 
Institute  of  Technology. 
Professor  Samuel  B.  Christy,  University  of  Cali- 
fornia. 

Secretary:   Dr.  Joseph  Struthers,  New  York  City. 

SECTION  E.    TECHNICAL  CHEMISTRY.    {Hall  16,  September  23, 10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  H.  W.  Wiley,  Department  of  Agriculture. 
Speakers:     Professor  Charles  E.  Munroe,  George  Washington 
University. 
Professor  William  H.  Walker,  Massachusetts  In- 
stitute of  Technology. 
Secretary:   Dr.  Marcus  Benjamin,  U.  S.  National  Museum. 

SECTION  F.    AGRICULTURE.    {Hall  10,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  H.  J.  Wheeler,  Kingston,  R.  I. 
Speakers:     Professor  Charles  W.  Dabney,  Jr.,  University  of 
Cincinnati. 
Professor  Liberty  H.  Bailey,  Cornell  University. 
Secretary:   Professor  William  Hill,  University  of  Chicago. 

DEPARTMENT   19  —  ECONOMICS 

{Hall  1,  September  20,  11.15  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Emory  R.  Johnson,  University  of  Penn- 
sylvania. 
Speakers:     Professor  Frank  A.  Fetter,  Cornell  University. 

Professor  Adolph  C.  Miller,    University    of    Cali- 
fornia. 

SECTION  A.    ECONOMIC  THEORY.     {Hall  15,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Professor  John  B.  Clark,  Columbia  University. 

Professor    Jacob    H.    Hollander,    Johns    Hopkins 
University. 

Professor  Jesse  E.  Pope,  University  of  Missouri. 


Secretary 
SECTION  B. 

Chairman  : 


TRANSPORTATION.     {Hall  10,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Professor   J.   Lawrence   Laughlin,   University   of 
Chicago. 
Speakers:     Professor    Eugene   von   Philippovich,    University 
of  Vienna. 
Professor  William  Z.  Ripley,  Harvard  University. 
Secretary:   Mr.  George  G.  Tunell.  Chicago. 


SPEAKERS  AND   CHAIRMEN  71 

SECTION  C.    COMMERCE  AND  EXCHANGE.       {Hall   10,    September   24, 
10  a.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Professor  E.  D.  Jones,  University  of  Michigan. 
Professor  Carl  Plehn,  University  of  California. 
Secretary : 

SECTION  D.    MONEY  AND  CREDIT.    (Hall  5,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Mr.  B.  E.  Walker,   Canadian   Bank   of  Commerce, 

Toronto. 
Speakers:     Mr.  Horace  White,  New  York  City. 

Professor   J.    Lawrence   Laughlin,   University   of 

Chicago. 
Secretary:   Professor  John  Cummings,  University  of  Chicago. 

SECTION  E.    PUBLIC  FINANCE.     {Hall  1,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman  : 

Speakers:     Professor  Henry  C.  Adams,  University  of  Michigan. 
Professor  Edwin  R.  A.  Seligman,  Columbia  Uni- 
versity. 
Secretary: 

SECTION  F.    INSURANCE.    {Hall  10,  September  21,  Z  p.  to.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  Emory  McClintock,  Actuary,  Mutual  Life  In 
surance  Company,  New  York. 

Speakers:     Mr.  Frederick  L.  Hoffman,  Statistician,  Prudential 
Insurance  Company,  Newark. 
Professor  Balthasar  H.  Meyer,  University  of  Wis- 
consin. 

Secretary : 


DIVISION   F  — SOCIAL   REGULATION 

{Hall  2,  September  20,  10  a.  to.) 
Speaker:       Professor  Abbott  L.  Lowell,  Harvard  University. 


DEPARTMENT  20  —  POLITICS 

{Hall  2,  September  20,  2  p.  to.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Professor  William  A.  Dunning,  Columbia  Univers- 
ity. 
Chancellor  E.   Benjamin  Andrews,  University  of 
Nebraska. 

SECTIONS  A  AND  C.     POLITICAL  THEORY  AND  NATIONAL  ADMINIS- 
TRATION.    {Hall  15,  September  22,  3  p.  to.) 

Chairman  : 

Speakers:     Professor  W.  W.  Willoughby,  Johns  Hopkins  Uni- 
versity. 


72  SPEAKERS  AND   CHAIRMEN 

Professor  George  G.  Wilson,  Brown  University. 
Right  Hon.  James  Bryce,  London,  England. 
Secretary:   Dr.  Charles  E.  Merriam,  University  of  Chicago. 

SECTION  B.    DIPLOMACY.    (Hall  1,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Honorable  John  W.  Foster,  Ex-Secretary  of  State. 
Honorable  David  Jayne  Hill,  Minister  of  the  United 
States  to  Switzerland. 
Secretary: 

SECTION  D.    COLONIAL    ADMINISTRATION.      {Hall    4,    September    24, 
10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  Harry  P.  Judson,  University  of  Chicago. 
Speakers  :     Professor  Bernard  J.  Moses,  University  of  California. 
Professor  Paul  S.  Reinsch,  University  of  Wisconsin. 
Secretary: 

SECTION  E.    MUNICIPAL  ADMINISTRATION.      {Hall  15,   September  24, 
3  p.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     Mr.  Albert  Shaw,  Editor  American  Monthly  Review 
of  Reviews. 
Miss  Jane  Addams,  Hull  House,  Chicago. 
Secretary:   Professor  John  A.  Fairlie,  University  of  Michigan. 

DEPARTMENT  21  —  JURISPRUDENCE 

{Hall  3,  September  20,  4.15  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  George  W.  Kirchwey,    Columbia    Uni- 
versity. 

Speakers:      President  Charles  W.  Needham,   Columbian  Uni- 
versity, Washington. 
Professor  Joseph  H.  Beale,  Harvard  University. 

SECTION  A.    INTERNATIONAL  LAW.    {Hall  14,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  James  B.  Scott,  Columbia  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  H.  LaFontaine,  Member  of  the  Senate, 
Brussels,  Belgium. 
Professor  Charles  Noble  Gregory,  University  of 

Iowa. 
Count  Albert  Apponyi,  Hungary. 
Secretary:   Dr.  W.  C.  Dennis,  Leland  Stanford  Jr.  University. 

SECTION  B.    CONSTITUTIONAL  LAW.    {Hall  14,  September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor    Henry    St.    George    Tucker,    George 

Washington  University,  Washington. 
Speakers:      Signor  Attilio  Brunialti,  Councilor  of  State,  Rome. 

Professor  John  W.  Burgess,  Columbia  University. 

Professor  Ferdinand  Larnaude,  University  of  Paris. 
Secretary : 


SPEAKERS  AND   CHAIRMEN 


73 


SECTION  C. 

Chaieman  : 
Speakees  : 


PRIVATE  LAW.    {Hall  14,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 
Peofessoe  James  B.  Ames,  Dean,  Harvard  Law  School. 


Peofessoe  Eenst  Feeund,  University  of  Chicago. 
HoNOEABLE  Edwaed  B.  Whitnet,  New  York. 
Seceetaet:   Dean  William  Deapee  Lewis,  University  of  Penn- 
sylvania. 


Chaieman; 

Speakees  : 


SECTION  A. 

Chaieman  : 

Speakees: 


Seceetaet: 
SECTION  B. 

Chaieman  : 

Speakees: 

Seceetaet : 

SECTION  C. 

Chaieman: 
Speakees  : 

Seceetaet : 

SECTION  D. 

Chaieman  : 
Speakees: 

Seceetaet : 
SECTION  E. 

Chaieman: 
Speakees  : 


Seceetaet : 

SECTION  F. 

Chaieman  : 
Speakee : 

Seceetaet : 


DEPARTMENT  22  — SOCIAL   SCIENCE 

{Hall  1,  September  20,  2  p.  m.) 

Me.  Waltee  L.  Sheldon,  Ethical  Society,  St.  Louis. 
Peofessoe  Felix  Adlee,  Columbia  University. 
Peofessoe    Geaham    Tatloe,    Chicago    Theological 

Seminary. 

THE  FAMILY.    {Hall  5,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Peofessoe  Samuel  G.  Smith,  University  of  Minnesota. 
De.  Samuel  W.  Dike,  Auburndale,  Mass. 
Peofessoe  Geoege  Elliott  Howaed,  University  of 
Nebraska. 

THE  RURAL  COMMUNITY.    {Hall  5,  September  21,  Z  p.  m.) 

Hon.  Aaeon  Jones,  Master  of  National  Grange,  South 

Bend,  Ind. 
Peofessoe  Max  Webee,  University  of  Heidelberg. 
Peesident  Kenton  L.  Butteefield,  Rhode  Island 

State  Agricultural  College. 
Peofessoe  William  Hill,  University  of  Chicago. 

THE  URBAN  COMMUNITY,    {Hall  5,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Peofessoe  T.  Jasteow,  University  of  Berlin. 
Peofessoe  Louis  Wuaein,  University  of  Geneva. 

THE  INDUSTRIAL  GROUP.    {Hall  14,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Peofessoe  Weenee  Sombaet,  University  of  Breslau. 
Peofessoe  Richaed  T.  Elt,  University  of  Wisconsin. 
Peofessoe  Thomas  S.  Adams,  Madison,  Wis. 

THE  DEPENDENT  GROUP.    {Hall  5,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Me.  Robeet  W.  DeFoeest,  New  York  City. 
Peofessoe  Chaeles    R.   Hendeeson,   University  of 

Chicago. 
De.  Emil    MtJNSTEEBEEG,    President    City  Charities, 

Berlin. 

THE  CRIMINAL  GROUP.    {Hall  5,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Me.  Feedeeick  H.  Wines,  Secretary  State  Charities 
Aid  Association,  Upper  Montclair,  N.  J. 


74 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


Speaker : 


DIVISION   G  — SOCIAL   CULTURE 

(Hall  5,  September  20,  10  a.  m.) 

Honorable  William  T,  Harris,  United  States  Com- 
missioner of  Education. 


DEPARTMENT  23  —  EDUCATION 

{Hall  2,  September  20,  4.15  p.  m.) 

Chairman: 

Speakers:     President  Arthur  T.  Hadley,  Yale  University. 

The  Right  Rev.  John  L.  Spalding,  Bishop  of  Peoria. 


SECTION  A.    EDUCATIONAL    THEORY.    {Hall  12,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Professor  Charles  DeGarmo,  Cornell  University. 
Professor  Wilhelm  Rein,  University  of  Jena. 
Professor  Elmer  E.  Brown,  University  of  Califor- 
nia. 
Dr.  G.  M.  Whittle,  Cornell  University. 


Chairman  : 
Speakers  : 


Secretary: 


SECTION  B.    THE  SCHOOL.     {Hall  12,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Dr.  F.  Louis  Soldan,  Superintendent  Public  Schools, 
St.  Louis. 

Speakers  :     Dr.  Michael  E.  Sadler,  University  of  Manchester. 
Dr.  William  H.  Maxwell,    Superintendent    Public 
Schools,  New  York  City. 

Secretary:   Professor   A.   S.   Langsdorf,  Washington  Univers- 
ity. 

SECTION  C.    THE  COLLEGE.     {Hall  12,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     President  W.  S.  Chaplin,  Washington  University. 
Speakers:     President  William  DeWitt  Hyde,  Bowdoin  College. 

President  M.  Carey  Thomas,  Bryn  Mawr  College. 
Secretary:   Professor  H.  H.  Horne,  Dartmouth  College. 

SECTION  D.    THE  UNIVERSITY.     {Hall  12,  September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman  : 

Speakers:     Professor  C.  Chabot,  University  of  Lyons. 

Professor  Edward  Delavan  Perry,  Columbia  Uni- 
versity. 
Secretary : 


SECTION  E.    THE  LIBRARY.    {Hall  12,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:     Mr.   Frederick   M.    Crunden,  Librarian    St.    Louis 

Public  Library. 
Speakers:      Mr.  William  A.  E.  Axon,  Manchester,  England. 

Professor  Guido  Biagi,  Royal  Librarian,  Florence. 
Secretary  :   Mr.  C.  P.  Pettus,  Washington  University. 


SPEAKERS  AND   CHAIRMEN 


75 


Chairman  : 
Speakers : 


SECTION  A. 

Chairman  : 
Speakers  : 

Secretary : 
SECTION  B. 

Chairman: 

Speakers  : 

Secretary : 

SECTION  C. 

Chairman: 

Speakers  : 
Secretary: 


SECTION  D. 

Chairman: 
Speakers  : 


Secretary : 


DEPARTMENT  24  —  RELIGION 

{Hall  4,  September  20,  4.15  p.  m.) 

Bishop  John  H.  Vincent,  Chautauqua,  N.  Y. 
President  Henry  C.  King,  Oberlin  College. 
Professor  Francis  G.  Peabody,  Harvard  University. 

GENERAL  RELIGIOUS  EDUCATION.  {Hall  11,  September 
24,  3  p.  m.) 

Professor  Edwin  D.  Starbuck,  Earlham  College, 
Richmond,  Ind. 

Professor  George  A.  Coe,  Northwestern  Univers- 
ity. 

Dr.  Walter  L.  Hervey,  Examiner  Board  of  Education, 
New  York  City. 

PROFESSIONAL  RELIGIOUS  EDUCATION.  {Hall  1,  Sep- 
tember 22,  3  p.  m.) 

President  Charles  Cuthbert  Hall,  Union  Theo- 
logical Seminary. 

Professor  Frank  K.  Sanders,  Yale  University. 

Professor  Herbert  L.  Willett,  Disciples  Divinity 
House,  Chicago,  lU. 

RELIGIOUS  AGENCIES.    {Hall  15,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

President  Edgar  G.  Mullins,  Southern  Baptist 
Theological  Seminary,  LouisviUe,  Ky. 

Rev.  Washington  Gladden,  Columbus,  Ohio. 

Rev.  James  M.  Buckley,  Editor  The  Christian  Ad- 
vocate, New  York. 

Dr.  Ira  Landrith,  General  Secretary  Religious  Edu- 
cation Association,  Chicago,  111. 

RELIGIOUS  WORK.    {Hall  1,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Rt.  Rev.  Thomas  F.  Gailor,  Memphis. 

Rev.  Floyd  W.  Tomkins,  Church  of  the  Holy  Trinity, 

Philadelphia. 
Rev.    Henry    C.    Mabie,    Corresponding    Secretary 

American  Baptist  Missionary  Union. 


SECTION  E.    RELIGIOUS  INFLUENCE:  PERSONAL.    {Festival  Hall,  Sep- 
tember 25,  10  a.  m.) 


Chairman: 
Speakers  : 


Secretary : 


Chancellor  J.  H.  Kirkland,  Vanderbilt  University. 
Rev.  Hugh  Black,  Edinburgh,  Scotland. 
Professor  John  E.  McFadyen,  Knox  CoUege. 
Rev.  Samuel  Eliot,  Boston,  Mass. 
Rev.  Edward  B.  Pollard,  Georgetown,  Ky. 
Professor  Clyde  W.  Votaw,  University  of  Chicago. 


76 


SPEAKERS  AND  CHAIRMEN 


SECTION  F.    RELIGIOUS  INFLUENCE:  SOCIAL.    (Festival  Hall,  Septem- 
ber 25,  3  p.  m.) 
Chairman:     Dr.  J.  H.  Garrison,  St.  Louis. 
Speakers:     President  Joseph  Swain,  Swarthmore  College. 
Dr.  Emil  G.  Hirsch,  Chicago,  111. 
Professor  Edward  C.  Moore,  Harvard  University. 
Dr.  Josiah  Strong,  League  for  Social  Service,  New 
York. 
Secretary:  Professor  Clyde  W.  Votaw,  University  of  Chicago. 


CHRONOLOGICAL  ORDER  OF  PROCEEDINGS 


MONDAY,    SEPTEMBER    19- 

3  P.  M.  Opening  exercises  of  the  Congress.  Festival  Hall  (Hall  17). 

The  Congress  will  be  called  to  order  by  the  Director  of  Congresses, 
who  will  introduce  the  President  of  the  Exposition. 

Welcoming  addresses  will  be  delivered  by  the  President  of  the 
Exposition  and  other  officials, 

A  reply  to  these  addresses  of  welcome  will  be  made  on  behalf  of  the 
Congress  by  the  Honorary  Vice-President  for  Great  Britain. 

The  Chairman  of  the  Administrative  Board  will  give  an  account  of 
the  origin  and  purpose  of  the  Congress. 

The  President  of  the  Congress  will  then  be  introduced  and  will 
deUver  an  introductory  address,  after  which  adjournment  will  follow. 


TUESDAY,    SEPTEMBER   20. 

10.00  A.  M.    Meetings  of  the  seven  Divisions.    The  Divisional  ad- 
dresses will  be  given  as  follows:  — 

Hall  1,  Utilitarian  Sciences.  Hall  5,  Social  Culture. 

Hall  2,  Social  Regulation.  Hall  6,  Normative  Science. 

Hall  3,  Historical  Science.  Hall  7,  Mental  Science. 
Hall  4,  Physical  Science. 

11.15  to  6.00  p.  M.  Meetings  of  the  Departments,  with  addresses:  — 
Meeting  at  11.15  a.  m.  Meeting  at  2  p.  m. 

DEPARTMENTS.  DEPARTMENTS. 

Hall  1,  Economics.  Hall  1,  Social  Science. 

Hall  2,  Biology.  Hall  2,  PoHtics. 

Hall  3,  Sciences  of  the  Earth.  Hall  3,  Technology. 

Hall  4,  Political  History.  Hall  4,  History  of  Language. 

Hall  5,  History  of  Law.  Hall  5,  History  of  Rehgion. 

Hall  6,  Philosophy.  '  Hall  6,  Physics. 

Hall  7,  Mathematics.  Hall  7,  Psychology. 

Hall  8,  History  of  Art.  Hall  8,  Anthropology. 

Adjournment  at  1  p.  m.  Adjournment  at  3.45  p.  m. 


78 


CHRONOLOGICAL  ORDER   OF   PROCEEDINGS 


Meeting  at  4.15  p.  m. 

DEPARTMENTS. 

Hall  1,  Medicine.  Hall  5,  Chemistry. 

HaU  2,  Education.  Hall  6,  History  of  Literature. 

Hall  3,  Jurisprudence.  Hall  7,  Sociology. 

Hall  4,  Religion.  Hall  8,  Astronomy. 

Adjournment  at  6.  p.  m. 

On  the  four  days  following,  the  Sectional  meetings  will  be  held. 
The  duration  of  each  session  will  be  three  hours.  The  morning  ses- 
sions will  extend  from  10  a.  m.  until  1  p.  m.;  the  afternoon  sessions 
from  3  P.  M.  to  6  p.  m. 

The  meetings  of  some  of  the  religious  sections  will  be  held  on 
Sunday,  September  25,  in  Festival  Hall.  Further  announcements 
concerning  these  Sunday  Meetings  will  be  made  in  Registration  Hall, 
in  the  daily  press  of  St.  Louis,  and  in  the  World's  Fair  Official  Pro- 
gramme. 


WEDNESDAY,    SEPTEMBER   21. 


Meeting  at  10  a.  m. 

1,  Public  Finance. 

2,  Animal  Morphology. 

3,  History  of  Greece,  Rome, 
and  Asia. 

4,  Comparative  Language. 

5,  The  FamUy. 

6,  Metaphysics. 

7,  Otology    and    Laryngo- 
logy. 

8,  Slavic  Literature. 

9,  Astrometry. 
Hall  10,  Civil  Engineering. 

HaU  11,  History  of  Common  Law. 
Hall  12,  Physiography. 
Hall  13,  Public  Health. 
Hall  14,  Geophysics. 
Hall  15,  Social  Structure. 
Hall  16,  Inorganic  Chemistry. 
Adjournment  at  1  p.  m. 


Hall 
HaU 
HaU 

Hall 
HaU 
Hall 
HaU 

HaU 
HaU 


Meeting  at  3  p.  m. 
Hall    1,  Philosophy  of  Religion. 
HaU    2,  Phylogeny. 
Hall    3,  Classical  Literature. 
Hall    4,  Semitic  Languages. 
Hall    5,  The  Rural  Community. 
Hall    6,  Medieval  History. 
Hall    7,  Pediatrics, 
Hall    8,  Oceanography. 
Hall    9,  Astrophysics. 
HaU  10,  Insurance. 
HaU  11,  History  of  Roman  Law. 
HaU  13,  Preventive  Medicine. 
Hall  14,  Geology. 
Hall  16,  Organic  Chemistry. 
Adjournment  at  6  p.  m. 


Immediately  following  the  Section  of  Geophysics  in  the  morning, 
and  the  Section  of  Geology  in  the  afternoon,  in  Room  14,  the  Eighth 
International  Geographic  Congress  will  hold  sessions  in  the  same 
room.  Hall  14,  Mines  and  Metallurgy  Building. 


CHRONOLOGICAL  ORDER  OF   PROCEEDINGS        79 

THURSDAY,   SEPTEMBER  22. 


Meeting  at  10  a.  m. 
Hall    1,  English  Literature. 
Hall    2,  Plant  Morphology. 
Hall    3,  Modern  History  of  Eu- 
rope. 
Hall    4,  Old  Testament. 
Hall    5,  The  Urban  Community. 
Hall    6,  Logic. 
HaU    7,  Psychiatry. 
Hall    8,  Indo-Iranian  Languages. 
Hall    9,  Algebra  and  Analysis. 
Hall  10,  Cosmical  Physics. 
Hall  11,  Palaeontology. 
Hall  12,  Classical  Art. 
Hall  13,  Pathology. 
Hall  14,  International  Law. 
Hall  15,  Economic  Theory. 
Hall  16,  Physical  Chemistry. 
Adjournment  at  1  p.  m. 


Meeting  at  3  p.  m. 

Hall    1,  Professional  Religious 
Education. 

Hall    2,  Human  Anatomy. 

Hall    3,  Greek  Language. 

HaU    4,  Plant  Physiology. 

Hall    5,  Physics  of  the  Electron. 

Hall    6,  Methodology  of  Science. 

Hall    7,  Modern  Architecture. 

Hall    8,  Romance  Literature. 

Hall    9,  Petrology  and  Mineral- 
ogy. 

HaU  10,  Electrical  Engineering. 

Hall  11,  Geography. 

HaU  12,  The  Library. 

HaU  13,  Neurology. 

Hall  14,  The  Industrial  Group. 

Hall  15,  PoHtical  Theory  and  Na- 
tional Administration. 

HaU  16,  Physiological  Chemistry. 
Adjournment  at  6  p.  m. 


FRIDAY,    SEPTEMBER   23. 


Meeting  at  10  a.  m. 
Hall    1,  New  Testament. 
Hall    2,  Experimental      Psycho- 
logy. 
Hall    3,  Germanic  Literature. 
Hall    4,  Physiology. 
Hall    5,  The  Dependent  Group. 
HaU    6,  Ethics. 
HaU    7,  Plant  Pathology. 
Hall    8,  Brahmanism  and  Buddh- 
ism. 
Hall    9,  Latin  Language. 
Hall  10,  Transportation. 
HaU  11,  Physics  of  Matter. 
HaU  12,  The  School.       . 
Hall  13,  Surgery. 
Hall  15,  Social  Psychology. 
Hall  16,  Technical  Chemistry. 
Adjournment  at  1  p.  m. 


Meeting  at  3  p.  m. 
Hall    1,  Diplomacy. 
Hall    2,  History  of  Economic  In- 
stitutions. 
Hall    3,  English  Language. 
HaU    4,  Esthetics. 
HaU    5,  The  Criminal  Group. 
HaU    6,  General  Psychology. 
HaU    7,  Ecology. 
HaU    8,  Mohammedism. 
HaU    9,  Embryology. 
HaU  10,  Mechanical  Engineering. 
HaU  11,  Physics  of  Ether. 
HaU  12,  The  CoUege. 
HaU  13,  Internal  Medicine. 
Hall  14,  Private  Law. 
HaU  15,  Religious  Agencies. 
Hall  16,  Somatology. 

Adjournment  at  6  p,  m. 


80 


CHRONOLOGICAL   ORDER  OF   PROCEEDINGS 


SATURDAY,    SEPTEMBER   24. 


Meeting  at  10  a.  m. 

1,  History  of  America, 

2,  History  of  the  Christian 
Church. 

3,  Belles-Lettres. 

4,  Colonial  Administration. 

5,  Romance  Languages. 

6,  Comparative  and  Gene- 
tic Psychology. 

7,  Ophthalmology. 

8,  History  of  Asia. 

9,  Geometry. 

Hall  10,  Commerce  and  Exchange. 

Hall  11,  Mining  Engineering. 

HaU  12,  The  University. 

Hall  13,  Gynecology. 

Hall  14,  Constitutional  Law. 

Hall  15,  Bacteriology. 

Hall  16,  Archaeology. 

Adjournment  at  1  p.  m. 


Hall 
Hall 

Hall 
Hall 
Hall 
Hall 

Hall 
Hall 
Hall 


Meeting  at  3  p.  m. 

Hall    1,  Religious  Work. 

Hall    2,  Comparative  Anatomy. 

Hall    3,  Germanic  Languages. 

Hall    4,  Modern  Painting. 

Hall    5,  Money  and  Credit. 

Hall    6,  Abnormal  Psychology. 

Hall    7,  Applied  Mathematics. 

Hall    8,  Indo-Iranian  Literature. 

Hall  10,  Agriculture. 

Hall  11, 

Hall  12,  Educational  Theory. 

Hall  13,  Therapeutics  and  Phar- 
liiacology. 

Hall  14,  Comparative  Law. 

Hall  15,  Municipal  Administra- 
tion. 

Hall  16,  Ethnology. 

Adjournment  at  6  p.  m. 


SUNDAY,  SEPTEMBER  25. 

Festival  Hall. 


Meeting  at  10  a.  m. 
Religious  Influence:  Personal. 


Meeting  at  3  p.  m. 
Religious  Influence:  Social. 


PROGRAMME   OF   SOCIAL    EVENTS 


Monday  Evening,  September  19.  —  Grand  Fete  night  in  honor 
of  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science.  Special  illuminations  about  the 
Grand  Basin.    Lagoon  fete. 

Banquet  by  the  St.  Louis  Chemical  Society,  at  the  Southern  Hotel, 
to  the  members  of  the  Chemical  Sections. 

Tuesday  Evening,  September  20.  —  General  Reception  by 
Board  of  Lady  Managers  to  the  officers  and  speakers  of  the  Congress 
and  officials  of  the  Exposition. 

Wednesday  Afternoon,  September  2L  —  Garden  fete  to  be 
given  to  the  members  of  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science,  at  the 
French  Pavilion,  by  the  Commissioner-General  from  France. 

Wednesday  Evening,  September  2L  —  General  reception  by  the 
German  Imperial  Commissioner-General  to  the  members  of  the  Con- 
gress of  Arts  and  Science,  at  the  German  State  House. 

Thursday  Evening.  —  Shaw  banquet  at  the  Buckingham  Club  to 
the  foreign  delegates. 

Friday  Evening,  September  23.  —  General  banquet  to  the 
speakers  and  officials  of  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science  in  the 
banquet-hall  of  the  Tyrolean  Alps.    8  p.  m. 

Saturday  Evening,  September  24.  —  Banquet  at  St.  Louis  Club 
by  Round  Table  of  St.  Louis,  to  the  foreign  members  of  the  Congress. 

Banquet  given  by  Imperial  Commissioner-General  from  Japan  to 
the  Japanese  delegation  to  the  Congress  and  Exposition  officials. 

Dinner  given  by  Commissioner-General  from  Great  Britain  to  the 
English  members  of  the  Congress. 


ALPHABETICAL  LIST   OF  MEMBERS 
WHO  MADE   10-MINUTE  ADDRESSES 


The  following  list  differs  from  the  original  programme,  in  that  it 
contains  the  names  only  of  those  who  actually  read  addresses.  It 
was  planned  that  each  Section  should  meet  for  three  hours.  When 
authors  of  ten-minute  papers  were  not  present,  and  where  not  enough 
of  these  shorter  papers  were  offered  to  fill  out  the  time,  the  Chairmen 
invited  discussions  from  the  floor  until  the  time  was  filled. 


Professor  R.  G.  Aitken 
James  W.  Alexander,  Esq. 
Frederick  Almy 
Professor  S.  G.  Aslimore 
Professor  L.  A.  Bauer 
Dr.  Marcus  Benjamin 
Professor  H.  T.  Blickfeldt 
Professor  Ernest  W.  Brown 
Dr.  Henry  Dickson  Bruns 

Dr.  F.  K.  Cameron 

Rear- Admiral  C.  M.  Chester, 

U.  S.  N. 
H.  H.  Clayton,  Esq. 
Professor  Charles  A.  Coffin 
Dr.  George  Coronilas 
Professor  J.  E.  Denton 

Professor  L.  W.  Dowling 
Professor  H.  C.  Elmer 
Professor  A.  Emch 
Professor  H.  R.  Fanclough 
Professor  W.  S.  Ferguson 

Dr.  Carlos  Finley 
Dr.  C.  E.  Fisk 
Homer  Folks,  Esq. 
Professor  F.  C.  French 
H.  L.  Gannt,  Esq. 

Dr.  F.  P.  Gorham 
Professor  Evarts  B.  Greene 
Stansbury  Hagar,  Esq. 
J.  D.  Hague,  Esq. 


Lick  Observatory 
New  York  City 
Buffalo,  N.  Y. 
Union  College 
Carnegie  Institute 
National  Museum 
Leland  Stanford  Univ. 
Haverford  College 
New  Orleans 

Dep't  of  Agriculture 
United    States    Naval 

Observatory 
Blue  Hill  Observatory 
New  York  City 
Athens,  Greece 
Stevens  Institute 

Univ.  of  Wisconsin 
Cornell  Univ. 
Univ.  of  Colorado 
Leland  Stanford  Univ. 
Univ.  of  CaHfornia 

Havana 
Centralia,  lU. 
New  York  City 
Univ.  of  Nebraska 
Schenectady,  N.  Y. 

Brown  Univ. 
Univ.  of  Illinois 
Brooklyn,  N.  Y. 
New  York  City 


Astronomy 
Insurance 
Social  Science 
Latin  Language 
Cosmical  Physios 
Technical  Chemistry 
Geometry 
Lunar  Theory 
Municipal  Administra- 
tion 
Physical  Chemistry 
Astronomy 

Cosmical  Physics 

Modern  Painting 

Tuberculosis 

Mechanical  Engineer- 
ing 

Geometry 

Latin  Language 

Geometry 

Classical  Literature 

History  of  Greece, 
Rome,  and  Asia 

Pathology 

History  of  America 

Social  Science 

Philosophy  of  Religion 

Mechanical  Engineer- 
ing 

Bacteriology 

History  of  America 

Ethnology 

Mining  Engineering 


MEMBERS   WHO  MADE   10-MINUTE  SPEECHES       83 


Professor  G.  B.  Halstead 
Professor  A.  D.  F.  Hamlin 
Professor  H.  Hancock 
Professor  J.  A.  Harris 
Professor  M.  W.  Haskell 
Professor  J.  T.  Hatfield 
Professor  E.  C.  Hayes 
Professor  W.  E.  Heidel 
Dr.  C.  L.  Herrick 
Dr.  C.  Judson  Herrick 
Professor  W.  H.  Hobbs 

Professor  A.  R.  Hohlfeld 
Professor  H.  H.  Home 
Dr.  E.  V.  Huntiagton 
Dr.  Reid  Hunt 
Dr.  J.  N.  Hurty 
Professor  J.  J.  Hutchinson 
Rev.  Thomas  E.  Judge 

Professor  L.  Kahlenburg 
Professor  Albert  G.  Keller 

Professor  George  Lefevre 
President  Henry  C.  King 
Dr.  Ira  Landrith 
Professor  M.  D.  Learned 
Professor  A.  O.  Leuschner 
Dr.  E.  P.  Lyon 
Dr.  Duncan  B.  Macdonald 

Professor  A.  MacFarlane 
Professor  James  McMahon 
Mr.  Edward  Mallinckrodt 
Professor  H.  P.  Manning 
Professor  G.  A.  MiUer 
Dr.  W.  C.  Mills 
Professor  W.  S.  Milner 
Professor  F.  G.  Moore 
Dr.  W.  P.  Montague 
Clarence  B.  Moore,  Esq. 
Professor  F.  R.  Moulton 
Dr.  J.  G.  Needham 
Professor  Alex.  T.  Ormond 
Professor  Frederic  L.  Paxton 
Dr.  Carl  Pfister 

Professor  M.  B.  Porter 
Dr.  A.  J.  Reynolds 
Professor  S.  P.  Sadtler 

Dr.  John  A.  Sampson 
Oswald  Schreiner,  Esq. 


Kenyon  College 
Columbia  Univ. 
Univ.  of  Cincinnati 
St.  Louis,  Mo. 
Univ.  of  California 
Northwestern  Univ. 
Miami  Univ. 
Iowa  CoUege 
GranvUle,  Ohio 
Granville,  Ohio 
Univ.  of  Wisconsin 

Univ.  of  Wisconsin 
Dartmouth  CoUege 
Harvard  Univ. 
U.  S.  Marine  Hospital 
Indianapolis,  Ind. 
Cornell  Univ. 
Catholic  Review  of  Re- 
views 
Univ.  of  Wisconsin 
Yale  University 

Univ.  of  Missouri 

OberUn  CoUege 

Belmont  CoUege 

Univ.  of  Pennsylvania 

Univ.  of  California 

St.  Louis  Univ. 

Hartford  Theological 
Seminary 

Chatham,  Ontario 

CorneU  Univ. 

St.  Louis,  Mo. 

Brown  Univ. 

Leland  Stanford  Univ. 

Ohio  State  Univ. 

Univ.  of  Toronto 

Dartmouth  CoUege 

Columbia  Univ. 

Philadelphia 

Univ.  of  Chicago 

Lake  Forest  Univ. 

Princeton  Univ. 

Univ.  of  Colorado 

St.  Mark's  Hospital, 
New  York  City 

Univ.  of  Texas 

Chicago 

Philadelphia  CoUege  of 
Pharmacy 

Albany,  N.  Y. 

U.  S.  Dep't  of  Agricul- 
ture 


Geometry 
Esthetics 
Geometry 
Plant  Morphology 
Algebra  and  Analysis 
Germanic  Language 
Social  Psychology 
Greek  Language 
Neurology 
Animal  Morphology 
Petrology  and  Mineral- 
ogy 
Germanic  Literature 
Educational  Theory 
Algebra  and  Analyses 
Alcohol,  etc. 
Public  Health 
Algebra  and  Analysis 
General  Religious  Edu- 
cation 
Physical  Chemistry 
Municipal  Administra- 
tion 
Comparative  Anatomy 
Education,  The  College 
Religious  Agencies 
Germanic  Literature 
Astronomy 
Physiology 
Semitic  Languages 

Applied  Mathematics 

AppUed  Mathematics 

Chemistry 

Geometry 

Algebra  and  Analysis. 

Archaeology 

Classical  Literature 

Classical  Literature 

Metaphysics 

Archaeology. 

Astronomy. 

Animal  Morphology 

Philosophy  of  ReUgion 

History  of  America 

Surgery 

Algebra  and  Analysis 

Public  Health 

Technical  Chemistry 
G5maecology 

Chemistry 


84       MEMBERS  WHO  MADE   10-MINUTE  SPEECHES 


Rev.  Frank  Sewall 

Professor  H.  C.  Sheldon 

Professor  Frank  C.  Sharp 
Professor  J.  B.  Shaw 
Professor  W.  B.  Smith 
Professor  Marshall  S.  Snow 
Professor  Henry  Snyder 
Professor  Edwain  D.  Starbuck 

Professor  George  B.  Stewart 

John  M.  Stahl 
Professor  J.  Stieglitz 
Professor  Robert  Stein 
Mr.  Teitaro  Suzuki 

Col.  T.  W.  Symonds,  U.  S.  A. 
Professor  Teissier 
Judge  W.  H.  Thomas 
Professor  O.  H.  Tittmann 
Professor  Alfred  M.  Tozzer 
Dr.  Benjamin  F.  Trueblood 
Professor  Clyde  W.  Votaw 
Professor  John  B.  Watson 
Professor  H.  L.  WiUett 

President  Mary  E.  WooUey 

H.  Zwaarddemaker 


Washington,  D.  C. 

Boston  Univ. 

Univ.  of  Wisconsin 
Milliken  Univ. 
Tulane  Univ. 
Washington  Univ. 
Univ.  of  Minnesota 
Earlham  College 

Auburn    Theological 

Seminary 
Quincy,  lU. 
Univ.  of  Chicago 
U.  S.  Geological  Survey 
La  SaUe,  111. 

Washington,  D.  C. 
Lyons,  France 
Montgomery,  Ala. 
U.  S.  C.  and  G.  Survey 
Peabody  Museum 
Univ.  of  Missouri 
Univ.  of  Chicago 
Univ.  of  Chicago 
Disciples    Divinity 

House,  Chicago 
Mt.  Holyoke  College 

Utrecht 


Social     Science,     The 
FamUy 

History  of  the  Chris- 
tian Church 

Ethics 

Algebra  and  Analysis 

New  Testament 

History  of  America 

Social  Science 

General  Religious  Edu- 
cation 

Professional    Religious 
Education 

The  Rural  Community 

Chemistry 

Comparative  Language 

Brahmanism     and 
Buddhism 

Civil  Engineering 

Pathology 

Private  Law 

Astronomy 

Anthropology 

Medieval  History 

New  Testament 

Psychology 

Professional    Religious 
Education 

Education,    The    Col- 
lege 

Otology  and  Laryngo- 
logy. 


THE    SCIENTIFIC  PLAN   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

BY  PROF.  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG 


I 

THE  PURPOSE  OF   THE   CONGRESS    . 

1.  The  Centralization  of  the  Congress 

The  history  of  the  Congress  has  been  told.  It  remains  to  set  forth  the 
principles  which  controlled  the  work  of  the  Congress  week,  and  thus 
scientifically  to  introduce  the  scholarly  undertaking,  the  results  of 
which  are  to  speak  for  themselves  in  the  eight  volumes  of  this  pub- 
lication. Yet  in  a  certain  way  this  scientific  introduction  has  once 
more  to  use  the  language  of  history.  It  does  not  deal  with  the  ex- 
ternal development  of  the  Congress,  and  the  story  which  it  has  to  tell 
is  thus  not  one  of  dates  and  names  and  events.  But  the  principles 
which  shaped  the  whole  undertaking  have  themselves  a  claim  to  his- 
torical treatment;  they  do  not  lie  before  us  simply  as  the  subject  for  a 
logical  disputation  or  as  a  plea  for  a  future  work.  That  was  the  situa- 
tion of  three  years  ago.  At  that  time  various  ideas  and  opposing 
principles  entered  into  the  arena  of  discussion;  but  now,  since  the 
work  is  completed,  the  question  can  be  only  of  what  principles,  right 
or  wrong,  have  really  determined  the  programme.  We  have  thus  to 
interpret  that  state  of  mind  out  of  which  the  purposes  and  the  scientific 
arrangement  of  the  Congress  resulted;  and  no  after-thought  of  to-day 
would  be  a  desirable  addition.  Whatever  possible  improvements  of 
the  plan  may  suggest  themselves  in  the  retrospect  can  be  given  only 
a  closing  word.  It  was  certainly  easy  to  learn  from  experience,  but 
first  the  experience  had  to  be  passed  through.  We  have  here  to  inter- 
pret the  view  from  that  standpoint  from  which  the  experience  of  the 
Congress  was  still  a  matter  of  the  future,  and  of  an  uncertain  future 
indeed,  full  of  doubts  and  fears,  and  yet  full  of  hopes  and  possibilities. 
The  St.  Louis  World's  Fair  promised,  through  the  vast  extent  of 
its  grounds,  through  the  beautiful  plans  of  the  buildings,  through  the 
eagerness  of  the  United  States,  through  the  participation  of  all  coun- 
tries on  earth,  and  through  the  gigantic  outlines  of  the  internal  plans, 
to  become  the  most  monumental  expression  of  the  energies  with 
which  the  twentieth  century  entered  on  its  course.  Commerce  and 
industry,  art  and  social  work,  politics  and  education,  war  and  peace, 


86         THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

country  and  city,  Orient  and  Occident,  were  all  to  be  focussed  for 
a  few  summer  months  in  the  ivory  city  of  the  Mississippi  Valley.  It 
seemed  most  natural  that  science  and  productive  scholarship  should 
also  find  its  characteristic  place  among  the  factors  of  our  modern 
civilization.  Of  course  the  scientist  had  his  word  to  say  on  almost  every 
square  foot  of  the  Exposition.  Whether  the  building  was  devoted  to 
electricity  or  to  chemistry,  to  anthropology  or  to  metallurgy,  to  civic 
administration  or  to  medicine,  to  transportation  or  to  industrial  arts, 
it  was  everywhere  the  work  of  the  scientist  which  was  to  win  the  tri- 
umph; and  the  Palace  of  Education,  the  first  in  any  universal  exposi- 
tion, was  to  combine  under  its  roof  not  only  the  school  work  of  all 
countries,  but  the  visible  record  of  the  world's  universities  and  tech- 
nical schools  as  well.  And  yet  it  seemed  not  enough  to  gather  the 
products  and  records  of  science  and  to  make  science  serve  with  its 
tools  and  inventions.  Modern  art,  too,  was  to  reign  over  every  hall 
and  to  beautify  every  palace,  and  yet  demanded  its  own  unfolding  in 
the  gallery  of  paintings  and  sculptures.  In  the  same  way  it  was  not 
enough  for  science  to  penetrate  a  hundred  exhibitions  and  turn  the 
wheels  in  every  hall,  but  it  must  also  seek  to  concentrate  all  its  ener- 
gies in  one  spot  and  show  the  cross-section  of  human  knowledge  in 
our  time,  and,  above  all,  its  own  methods. 

An  exhibition  of  scholarship  cannot  be  arranged  for  the  eyes.  The 
great  work  which  grows  day  by  day  in  quiet  libraries  and  laboratories, 
and  on  a  thousand  university  platforms,  can  express  itself  only 
through  words.  Yet  heaped  up  printed  volumes  would  be  dead  to 
a  World's  Fair  spectator;  how  to  make  such  words  living  was  the 
problem.  Above  all,  scholarship  does  not  really  exhibit  its  methods, 
if  it  does  not  show  itself  in  production.  It  is  no  longer  scholarship 
which  speaks  of  a  truth-seeking  that  has  been  performed  instead  of 
going  on  with  the  search  for  further  truth.  If  the  world's  science  was 
to  be  exhibited,  a  form  had  to  be  sought  in  which  the  scholarly 
work  on  the  spot  would  serve  the  ideals  of  knowledge,  would  add  to 
the  storehouse  of  truth,  and  would  thus  work  in  the  service  of  human 
progress  at  the  same  moment  in  which  it  contributed  to  the  com- 
pleteness of  the  exhibition. 

The  effort  was  not  without  precedent.  Scholarly  production  had 
been  connected  with  earlier  expositions,  and  the  large  gatherings  of 
scholars  at  the  Paris  Exposition  were  still  in  vivid  memory.  A  large 
number  of  scientific  congresses  of  specialists  had  been  held  there,  and 
many  hundred  scholarly  papers  had  been  read.  Yet  the  results  hardly 
suggested  the  repetition  of  such  an  experiment.  Every  one  felt  too 
strongly  that  the  outcome  of  such  disconnected  congresses  of  special- 
ists is  hardly  comparable  with  the  glorious  showing  which  the  arts 
and  industries  have  made  and  were  to  make  again.  In  every  other 
department  of  the  World's  Fair  the  most  careful  preparation  secured 


THE  CENTRALIZATION   OF   THE  CONGRESS         87 

an  harmonious  effect.  The  scholarly  meetings  alone  failed  even  to  aim 
at  harmony  and  unity.  Not  only  did  the  congresses  themselves  stand 
apart  without  any  inner  relation,  grouped  together  by  calendar  dates 
or  by  their  alphabetical  order  from  Anthropology  to  Zoology;  but 
in  every  congress,  again,  the  papers  read  and  the  manuscripts  pre- 
sented were  disconnected  pieces  without  any  programme  or  correla- 
tion. Worse  than  that,  they  could  not  even  be  expected  in  their  isolat- 
edness  to  add  anything  which  would  not  have  been  worked  out  and 
communicated  to  the  world  just  as  well  without  any  congress.  The 
speaker  at  such  a  meeting  is  asked  to  contribute  anything  he  has  at 
hand,  and  he  accepts  the  invitation  because  he  has  by  chance  a  com- 
pleted paper  or  a  research  ready  for  publication.  In  the  best  case  it 
would  have  appeared  in  the  next  number  of  the  specialistic  magazine, 
in  not  unfrequent  cases  it  has  appeared  already  in  the  last  number. 
Such  a  congress  is  then  only  an  accident  and  does  not  itself  serve  the 
progress  of  knowledge. 

Even  that  would  be  acceptable  if  at  least  the  best  scholars  would 
come  out  with  their  latest  investigations,  or,  still  more  delightful,  if 
they  would  enter  into  an  important  discussion.  But  experience  has 
too  often  shown  that  the  conditions  are  most  favorable  for  the  oppo- 
site outcome.  The  leading  scholars  stay  away  partly  to  give  beginners 
the  chance  to  be  heard,  partly  not  to  be  grouped  with  those  who 
habitually  have  the  floor  at  such  gatherings.  These  are  either  the  men 
whose  day  has  gone  by  or  those  whose  day  has  not  yet  come;  and 
both  groups  tyrannize  alike  an  unwilling  audience.  Yet  it  may  be  said 
that  in  scientific  meetings  of  specialists  the  reading  of  papers  is  non- 
essential and  no  harm  is  done  even  if  they  do  not  contribute  anything 
to  the  status  of  scholarship ;  their  great  value  lies  in  the  personal  con- 
tact of  fellow  workers  and  in  the  discussions  and  informal  exchange  of 
opinions.  All  that  is  true,  and  completely  justifies  the  yearly  meetings 
of  scholarly  associations.  But  these  advantages  are  much  diminished 
whenever  such  gatherings  take  on  an  international  character,  and 
thus  introduce  the  confusion  of  tongues.  And  hardly  any  one  can 
doubt  that  the  turmoil  of  a  world's  fair  is  about  the  worst  possible 
background  for  such  exchange  of  thought,  which  demands  repose  and 
quietude.  Yet  even  with  the  certainty  of  all  these  disadvantages  the 
city  of  Paris,  with  its  large  body  of  scholars,  with  its  venerable  schol- 
arly traditions,  and  with  its  incomparable  attractions,  could  overcome 
every  resistance,  and  its  convenient  location  made  it  natural  that  in 
vacation  time,  in  an  exposition  summer,  the  scholars  should  gather 
there,  not  on  account  of,  but  in  spite  of,  the  hundred  congresses. 
With  this  the  city  of  St.  Louis  could  make  no  claim  to  rivalry.  Its 
recent  growth,  its  minimum  of  scholarly  tradition,  its  great  distance 
from  the  old  centres  of  knowledge  even  in  the  New  World,  the  apathy 
of  the  East  and  the  climatic  fears  of  Europe,  all  together  made  it  clear 


88         THE   SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

that  a  mere  repetition  of  unrelated  congresses  would  be  not  only 
uselesS;  but  a  disastrous  failure.  These  very  fears,  however,  them- 
selves suggested  the  remedy. 

If  the  scholarly  work  of  our  time  was  to  be  represented  at  St.  Louis, 
something  had  to  be  attempted  which  should  be  not  simply  an  imita- 
tion of  the  branch-congresses  which  every  scientific  specialty  in  every 
country  is  calling  every  year.  Scholarship  was  to  be  asked  to  show 
itself  really  in  process,  and  to  produce  for  the  World's  Fair  meeting 
something  which  without  it  would  remain  undone.  To  invite  the 
scholars  of  the  world  for  their  leisurely  enjoyment  and  reposeful  dis- 
cussion of  work  done  elsewhere  is  one  thing;  to  call  them  together 
for  work  which  they  would  not  do  otherwise,  and  which  ought  to  be 
done,  is  a  very  different  thing.  The  first  had  in  St.  Louis  all  odds 
against  it;  it  seemed  worth  while  to  try  the  second.  And  it  seemed 
not  only  worth  while  in  the  interest  of  scholarship,  it  seemed,  above 
all,  the  only  way  to  give  to  the  scholarship  of  our  time  a  chance  for 
the  complete  demonstration  of  its  productive  energies. 

The  plan  of  unrelated  congresses,  with  chance  combinations  of 
papers  prepared  at  random,  was  therefore  definitively  replaced  by  the 
plan  of  only  one  representative  gath^ering,  bound  together  by  one 
underlying  thought,  given  thus  the  unity  of  one  scholarly  aim,  whose 
fulfillment  is  demanded  by  the  scientific  needs  of  our  time,  and  is 
hardly  to  be  reached  by  other  methods.  Every  arbitrary  and  indi- 
vidual choice  was  then  to  be  eliminated  and  every  effort  was  to  be 
controlled  by  the  one  central  purpose;  the  work  thus  to  be  organized 
and  prepared  with  the  same  carefulness  of  adjustment  and  elabora- 
tion which  was  doubtless  to  be  applied  in  the  admirable  exhibitions 
of  the  United  States  Government  or  in  the  art  exhibition.  The  open 
question  was,  of  course,  what  topic  could  fulfill  these  various  demands 
most  completely;  wherein  lay  the  greatest  scholarly  need  of  our  time; 
what  task  could  be  least  realized  by  the  casual  efforts  of  scholarship 
at  random;  where  was  the  unity  of  a  world  organization  most  needed? 

One  thought  was  very  naturally  suggested  by  the  external  circum- 
stances. St.  Louis  had  asked  the  nations  of  the  world  to  a  celebration 
of  the  Louisiana  Purchase.  Historical  thoughts  thus  gave  meaning 
and  importance  to  the  whole  undertaking.  The  pride  of  one  century's 
development  had  stimulated  the  gigantic  work  from  its  inception.  An 
immense  territory  had  been  transformed  from  a  half  wilderness  into 
a  land  with  a  rich  civilization,  and  with  a  central  city  in  which  eight 
thousand  factories  are  at  work.  No  thought  lay  nearer  than  to  ask 
how  far  this  century  was  of  similar  importance  for  the  changes  in  the 
world  of  thought.  How  have  the  sciences  developed  themselves  since 
the  days  of  the  Louisiana  Purchase?  That  is  a  topic  which  with  com- 
plete uniformity  might  be  asked  from  every  special  science,  and  which 
might  thus  offer  a  certain  unity  of  aim  to  scholars  of  all  scientific  de- 


THE  CENTRALIZATION   OF   THE  CONGRESS         89 

nominations.  There  was  indeed  no  doubt  that  such  an  historical  ques- 
tion would  have  to  be  raised  if  we  were  to  live  up  to  the  commemora- 
tive idea  of  the  whole  Fair.  And  yet  it  seemed  still  more  certain  that 
the  retrospective  problem  did  not  justify  itself  as  a  central  topic  for  a 
World's  Congress.  There  were  sciences  for  which  the  story  of  the  last 
hundred  years  was  merely  the  last  chapter  of  a  history  of  three  thou- 
sand years  and  other  sciences  whose  life  history  did  not  begin  until 
one  or  two  decades  ago.  It  would  thus  be  a  very  external  uniformity; 
the  question  would  have  a  very  different  meaning  for  the  various 
branches  of  knowledge,  and  the  treatment  would  be  of  very  unequal 
interest  and  importance.  More  than  that,  it  would  not  abolish  the 
unrelated  character  of  the  endeavors;  while  the  same  topic  might 
be  given  everywhere,  yet  every  science  would  remain  isolated;  there 
would  be  no  internal  unity,  and  thus  no  inner  reason  for  bringing 
together  the  best  workers  of  all  spheres.  And  finally  the  mere  retro- 
spective attitude  brings  with  it  the  depressing  mood  of  perfunctory 
activity.  Certainly  to  look  back  on  the  advance  of  a  century  can  be 
most  suggestive  for  a  better  understanding  of  the  way  which  lies 
before  us;  and  we  felt  indeed  that  the  occasion  for  such  a  back- 
ward glance  ought  not  to  be  missed.  Yet  there  would  be  something 
lifeless  if  the  whole  meeting  were  devoted  to  the  consideration  of  work 
that  had  been  completed;  a  kind  of  necrological  sentiment  would 
pervade  the  whole  ceremony,  while  our  chief  aim  was  to  serve  the 
progress  of  knowledge  and  thus  to  stimulate  living  interests. 

This  language  of  life  spoke  indeed  in  the  programme  of  another 
plan  which  seemed  also  to  be  suggested  by  the  character  of  the 
Exposition.  The  St.  Louis  Fair  desired  not  merely  to  look  backward 
and  to  revive  the  historical  interest  in  the  Louisiana  Purchase, 
but  its  first  aim  seemed  to  be  to  bring  into  sharp  relief  the  factors 
which  serve  to-day  the  practical  welfare  and  the  achievements  of 
human  society.  If  all  the  scholars  of  all  sciences  were  to  convene 
under  one  flag,  would  it  not  thus  seem  most  harmonious  with  the 
occasion,  if,  as  the  one  controlling  topic,  the  question  were  proposed, 
"  What  does  your  science  contribute  to  the  practical  progress  of  man- 
kind? "  No  one  can  deny  that  such  a  formulation  would  fit  in  well 
with  the  lingering  thoughts  of  every  World's  Fair  visitor.  Whoever 
wanders  through  the  aisles  of  exhibition  palaces  and  sees  amassed  the 
marvelous  achievements  of  industry  and  commerce,  and  the  thousand 
practical  arts  of  modern  society,  may  indeed  turn  most  naturally  to 
a  gathering  of  scholars  with  the  question,  '■'  What  have  you  to  offer 
of  similar  import?"  All.  your  thinking  and  speaking  and  writing,  are 
they  merely  words  on  words,  or  do  you  also  turn  the  wheels  of  this 
gigantic  civilization? 

Such  a  question  would  give  a  noble  opening  indeed  to  almost  every 
science.  Who  would  say  that  the  opportunity  is  confined  to  the  man  of 


90         THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

technical  science?  Does  not  the  biologist  also  prepare  the  achievements 
of  modern  medicine,  does  not  the  mathematician  play  his  most  impor- 
tant role  in  our  mastery  over  stubborn  nature,  do  we  not  need  lan- 
guage for  our  social  intercourse,  and  law  and  religion  for  our  practical 
social  improvement?  Yes,  is  there  any  science  which  has  not  directly 
or  indirectly  something  to  contribute  to  the  practical  development  of 
the  modern  man  and  his  civilization?  All  this  is  true,  and  yet  the 
perspective  of  this  truth,  too,  appears  at  once  utterly  distorted  if  we 
take  the  standpoint  of  science  itself.  The  one  end  of  knowledge  is  to 
reach  the  truth.  The  belief  in  the  absolute  value  of  truth  gives  to  it 
meaning  and  significance.  This  value  remains  the  controlling  influ- 
ence even  where  the  problem  to  be  solved  is  itself  a  practical  one,  and 
the  spirit  of  science  remains  thus  essentially  theoretical  even  in  the 
so-called  applied  sciences.  But  incomparably  more  intense  in  that 
respect  is  the  spirit  of  all  theoretical  disciplines.  Philosophy  and 
mathematics,  history  and  philology,  chemistry  and  biology,  astro- 
nomy and  geology,  may  be  and  ought  to  be  helpful  to  practical 
civilization  everywhere;  and  every  step  forward  which  they  take 
will  be  an  advance  for  man's  practical  life  too.  And  yet  their  real 
meaning  never  lies  in  their  technical  by-product.  It  is  not  the 
scholar  who  peers  in  the  direction  of  practical  use  who  is  most  loyal 
to  the  deepest  demand  of  scholarship,  and  every  relation  to  prac- 
tical achievement  is  more  or  less  accidental  or  even  artificial  for 
the  real  life  interests  of  productive  scholarship. 

But  if  the  contrast  between  his  real  intention  and  his  social  tech- 
nical successes  may  not  appear  striking  to  the  physicist  or  chemist, 
it  would  appear  at  least  embarrassing  to  the  scholars  in  many  other 
departments  and  directly  bewildering  to  not  a  few.  Perhaps  two 
thirds  of  the  sciences  to  which  the  best  thinkers  of  our  time  are  faith- 
fully devoted  would  then  be  grouped  together  and  relegated  to  a 
distant  corner,  their  only  practical  technical  function  would  be  to 
contribute  material  to  the  education  of  the  cultured  man.  For  what 
else  do  we  study  Sanscrit  or  medieval  history  or  epistemology?  And 
finally  even  the  uniform  topic  of  practical  use  would  not  have 
brought  the  different  sciences  nearer  to  each  other;  the  Congress 
would  still  have  remained  a  budget  of  disconnected  records  of  scholar- 
ship. If  the  practical  side  of  the  Exposition  was  to  suggest  anything, 
it  should  then  not  be  more  than  an  appeal  not  to  overlook  the  impor- 
tance of  the  applied  sciences  which  too  often  play  the  r61e  of  a  mere 
appendix  to  the  system  of  knowledge.  The  logical  one-sidedness 
which  considers  practical  needs  as  below  the  dignity  of  pure  science 
was  indeed  to  be  excluded,  but  to  choose  practical  service  as  the  one 
controlling  topic  would  be  far  more  anti-scientific. 


THE  UNITY  OF   KNOWLEDGE  91 

2.    The  Unity  of  Knowledge 

There  was  another  side  of  the  Exposition  plan  which  suggested  a 
stronger  topic.  The  World's  Fair  was  not  only  an  historical  memorial 
work,  and  was  not  only  a  show  of  the  practical  tools  of  technical  civil- 
ization; its  deepest  aim  was  after  all  the  effort  to  bring  the  energies  of 
our  time  into  inner  relation.  The  peoples  of  the  whole  globe,  sepa- 
rated by  oceans  and  mountains,  by  language  and  custom,  by  politics 
and  prejudice,  were  here  to  come  in  contact  and  to  be  brought  into 
correlation  by  better  mutual  understanding  of  the  best  features  of 
their  respective  cultures.  The  various  industries  and  arts,  the  most 
antagonistic  efforts  of  commerce  and  production,  separated  by  the 
rivalry  of  the  market  and  by  the  diversity  of  economic  interests 
were  here  to  be  brought  together  in  harmony,  were  to  be  correlated 
for  the  eye  of  the  spectator.  It  was  a  near-lying  thought  to  choose 
correlation  as  the  controlling  thought  of  a  scientific  World's  Congress 
too.  That  was  the  topic  which  was  finally  agreed  upon:  the  inner 
relation  of  the  sciences  of  our  day. 

The  fitness  and  the  external  advantages  of  such  a  scheme  are 
evident.  First  of  all,  the  danger  of  disconnectedness  now  disappears 
completely.  If  the  sciences  are  to  examine  what  binds  them  together, 
their  usual  isolation  must  be  given  up  for  the  time  being  and  a  con- 
certed effort  must  control  the  day.  The  bringing  together  of  scholars 
of  all  scientific  specialties  is  then  no  longer  a  doubtful  accidental  fea- 
ture, but  becomes  a  condition  of  the  whole  undertaking.  More  than 
that,  such  a  topic,  with  all  that  it  involves,  makes  it  a  matter  of  course 
that  the  call  goes  out  to  the  really  leading  scholars  of  the  time.  To 
aim  at  a  correlation  of  sciences  means  to  seek  for  the  fundamental 
principles  in  each  territory  of  knowledge  and  to  look  with  far-seeing 
eye  beyond  the  limits  of  its  field;  but  just  this  excludes  from  the 
outset  those  who  like  to  be  the  self-appointed  speakers  in  routine 
gatherings.  It  excludes  from  the  first  the  narrow  specialist  who  does 
not  care  for  anything  but  for  his  latest  research,  and  ought  to  exclude 
not  less  the  vague  spirits  who  generalize  about  facts  of  which  they 
have  no  concrete  substantial  knowledge,  as  their  suggestions  towards 
correlation  would  lack  inner  productiveness  and  outer  authority. 
Such  a  plan  has  room  only  for  those  men  who  stand  high  enough  to 
see  the  whole  field  and  who  have  yet  the  full  authority  of  the  special- 
istic  investigator;  they  must  combine  the  concentration  on  specialized 
productive  work  with  the  inspiration  that  comes  from  looking  over 
vast  regions.  With  such  a  topic  the  usual  question  does  not  come  up 
whether  one  or  another  strong  man  would  feel  attracted  to  take  part 
in  the  gathering,  but  it  would  be  justified  and  necessary  to  confine  the 
active  participation  from  the  outset  to  those  who  are  leaders,  and 
thus  to  guarantee  from  the  beginning  a  representation  of  science 


92         THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF   THE  CONGRESS 

equal  in  dignity  to  the  best  efforts  of  the  exhibiting  countries  in  all 
other  departments.  In  this  way  such  a  plan  had  the  advantage  of 
justifying  through  its  topic  the  administrative  desire  to  bring  all 
sciences  to  the  same  spot,  and  at  the  same  time  of  excluding  all  par- 
ticipants but  the  best  scholars:  with  isolated  gatherings  or  with 
second-rate  men,  this  subject  would  have  been  simply  impossible. 

Yet  all  these  halfway  external  advantages  count  Uttle  compared 
with  the  significance  and  importance  of  the  topic  for  the  inner  Hfe  of 
scientific  thought  of  our  time.  We  aU  felt  it  was  the  one  topic  which 
the  beginning  of  the  twentieth  century  demanded  and  which  could 
not  be  dealt  with  otherwise  than  by  the  combined  labors  of  all  nations 
and  of  all  sciences.  The  World's  Fair  was  the  one  great  opportunity 
to  make  a  first  effort  in  this  direction;  we  had  no  right  to  miss  this 
opportunity.  Thus  it  was  decided  to  have  a  congress  with  the  definite 
purpose  of  working  towards  the  unity  of  human  knowledge,  and  with 
the  one  mission,  in  this  time  of  scattered  speciahzing  work,  of  bringing 
to  the  consciousness  of  the  world  the  too-much  neglected  idea  of  the 
unity  of  truth.  To  quote  from  our  first  tentative  programme:  "  Let 
the  rush  of  the  world's  work  stop  for  one  moment  for  us  to  consider 
what  are  the  underlying  principles,  what  are  their  relations  to  one 
another  and  to  the  whole,  what  are  their  values  and  purposes;  in 
short,  let  us  for  once  give  to  the  world's  sciences  a  hohday.  The  work- 
aday functions  are  much  better  fulfilled  in  separation,  when  each 
scholar  works  in  his  own  laboratory  or  in  his  hbrary;  but  this  holiday 
task  of  bringing  out  the  underlying  unity,  this  synthetic  work,  this 
demands  really  the  cooperation  of  all,  this  demands  that  once  at  least 
all  sciences  come  together  in  one  place  at  one  time." 

Yet  if  our  work  stands  for  the  unity  of  knowledge,  aims  to  consider 
the  fundamental  conceptions  which  bind  together  all  the  specialistic 
results,  and  seeks  to  inquire  into  the  methods  which  are  common  to 
various  fields,  all  this  is  after  all  merely  a  symptom  of  the  whole  spirit 
of  our  times.  A  reaction  against  the  narrowness  of  mere  fact-diggers 
has  set  in.  A  mere  heaping  up  of  disconnected,  unshaped  facts  begins 
to  disappoint  the  world;  it  is  felt  too  vividly  that  a  mere  dictionary  of 
phenomena,  of  events  and  laws,  makes  our  knowledge  larger  but  not 
deeper,  makes  our  Hfe  more  complex  but  not  more  valuable,  makes 
our  science  more  difficult  but  not  more  harmonious.  Our  time  longs 
for  a  new  synthesis  and  looks  towards  science  no  longer  merely  with 
a  desire  for  technical  prescriptions  and  new  inventions  in  the  interest 
of  comfort  and  exchange.  It  waits  for  knowledge  to  fulfill  its  higher 
mission,  it  waits  for  science  to  satisfy  our  higher  needs  for  a  view 
of  the  world  which  shall  give  unity  to  our  scattered  experience.  The 
indications  of  this  change  are  visible  to  every  one  who  observes  the 
gradual  turning  to  philosophical  discussion  in  the  most  different 
fields  of  scientific  life. 


THE  UNITY  OF   KNOWLEDGE  93 

When  after  the  first  third  of  the  nineteenth  century  the  great 
philosophic  movement  which  found  its  cUmax  in  HegeUanism  came 
to  disaster  in  consequence  of  its  absurd  neglect  of  hard  solid  facts,  the 
era  of  naturalism  began  its  triumph  with  contempt  for  all  philosophy 
and  for  all  deeper  unity.  IdeaHsm  and  philosophy  were  stigmatized  as 
the  enemies  of  true  science  and  natural  science  had  its  great  day.  The 
rapid  progress  of  physics  and  chemistry  fascinated  the  world  and  pro- 
duced modern  technique;  the  sciences  of  life,  physiology,  biology, 
medicine,  followed;  and  the  scientific  method  was  carried  over  from 
body  to  mind,  and  gave  us  at  the  end  of  the  nineteenth  century  mod- 
ern psychology  and  sociology.  The  lifeless  and  the  living,  the  physical 
and  the  mental,  the  individual  and  the  social,  all  had  been  conquered 
by  analytical  methods.  But  just  when  the  cUmax  was  reached  and  all 
had  been  analyzed  and  explained,  the  time  was  ripe  for  disillusion, 
and  the  lack  of  deeper  unity  began  to  be  felt  with  alarm  in  every 
quarter.  For  seventy  years  there  had  been  nowhere  so  much  philo- 
sophizing going  on  as  suddenly  sprung  up  among  the  scientists  of 
the  last  decade.  The  physicists  and  the  mathematicians,  the  chemists 
and  the  biologists,  the  geologists  and  the  astronomers,  and,  on  the 
other  side,  the  historians  and  the  economists,  the  psychologists  and 
the  sociologists,  the  jurists  and  the  theologians  —  all  suddenly  found 
themselves  again  in  the  midst  of  discussions  on  fundamental  princi- 
ples and  methods,  on  general  categories  and  conditions  of  knowledge, 
in  short,  in  the  midst  of  the  despised  philosophy.  And  with  those 
discussions  has  come  the  demand  for  correlation.  Everywhere  have 
arisen  leaders  who  have  brought  unconnected  sciences  together  and 
emphasized  the  unity  of  large  divisions.  The  time  seems  to  have  come 
again  when  the  wave  of  naturalism  and  realism  is  ebbing,  and  a  new 
idealistic  philosophical  tide  is  swelling,  just  as  they  have  always  alter- 
nated in  the  civilization  of  two  thousand  years. 

No  one  dreams,  of  course,  that  the  great  synthetic  apperception,  for 
which  our  modern  time  seems  ripe,  will  come  through  the  delivery  of 
some  hundred  addresses,  or  the  discussions  of  some  hundred  audiences. 
An  ultimate  unity  demands  the  gigantic  thought  of  a  single  genius, 
and  the  work  of  the  many  can,  after  all,  be  merely  the  preparation 
for  the  final  work  of  the  one.  And  yet  history  shows  that  the  one  will 
never  come  if  the  many  have  not  done  their  share.  What  is  needed 
is  to  fill  the  sciences  of  our  time  with  the  growing  consciousness  of 
belonging  together,  with  the  longing  for  fundamental  principles,  with 
the  conviction  that  the  desire  for  correlation  is  not  the  fancy  of 
dreamers,  but  the  immediate  need  of  the  leaders  of  thought.  And  in 
this  preparatory  work  the  St.  Louis  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science 
seemed  indeed  called  for  an  important  part  when  it  was  committed 
to  this  topic  of  correlation. 

To  call  the  scholars  of  the  world  together  for  concerted  action 


94         THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

towards  the  correlation  of  knowledge  meant,  of  course,  first  of  all,  to 
work  out  a  detailed  programme,  and  to  select  the  best  authorities 
for  every  special  part  of  the  whole  scheme.  Nothing  could  be  left  to 
chance  methods  and  to  casual  contributions.  The  preparation  needed 
the  same  administrative  strictness  which  would  be  demanded  for  an 
encyclopedia,  and  the  same  scholarly  thoroughness  which  would  be 
demanded  for  the  most  scientific  research.  A  plan  was  to  be  devised 
in  which  every  possible  striving  for  truth  would  find  its  place,  and 
in  which  every  section  would  have  its  definite  position  in  the  system. 
And  such  a  ground-plan  given,  topics  were  to  be  assigned  to  every 
department  and  sub-department,  the  treatment  of  which  would  bring 
out  the  fundamental  principles  and  the  inner  relations  in  such  a  way 
that  the  papers  would  finally  form  a  close-woven  intellectual  fabric. 
There  would  be  plenty  of  room  for  a  retrospective  glance  at  the  his- 
torical development  of  the  sciences  and  plenty  of  room  for  emphasis 
on  their  practical  achievements;  but  the  central  place  would  always 
belong  to  the  effort  towards  unity  and  internal  harmonization. 

We  thus  divided  human  knowledge  into  large  parts,  and  the  parts 
into  divisions,  and  the  divisions  into  departments,  and  the  depart- 
ments into  sections.  As  the  topic  of  the  general  divisions  —  we  pro- 
posed seven  of  them  —  it  was  decided  to  discuss  the  Unity  of  the 
whole  field.  As  topic  for  the  departments  —  we  had  twenty-four  of 
them  —  the  addresses  were  to  discuss  the  fundamental  Conceptions 
and  Methods  and  the  Progress  during  the  last  century;  and  in  the 
sections,  finally  —  our  plan  provided  for  one  hundred  and  twenty- 
eight  of  them  —  the  topics  were  in  every  one  the  Relation  of  the 
special  branch  to  other  branches,  and  those  most  important  Present 
Problems  which  are  essential  for  the  deeper  principles  of  the  special 
field.  In  this  way  the  ground-plan  itself  suggested  the  unity  of  the 
practically  separated  sciences;  and,  moreover,  our  plan  provided 
from  the  first  that  this  logical  relation  should  express  itself  externally 
in  the  time  order  of  the  work.  We  were  to  begin  with  the  meetings  of 
the  large  divisions,  the  meetings  of  the  departments  were  to  foUow, 
and  the  meetings  of  the  sections  and  their  ramifications  would  follow 
the  departmental  gatherings. 

3.    The  Objections  to  the  Plan 

It  was  evident  that  even  the  most  modest  success  of  that  gigantic 
imdertaking  depended  upon  the  right  choice  of  speakers,  upon  the 
value  of  the  ground-plan,  and  upon  many  external  conditions;  thus 
no  one  was  in  doubt  as  to  the  difficulty  in  realizing  such  a  scheme. 
Yet  there  were  from  the  scholarly  side  itself  objections  to  the  prin- 
ciples involved,  objections  which  might  hold  even  if  those  other 
conditions  were  successfully  met.    The  most  immediate  reason  for 


THE  OBJECTIONS  TO  THE  PLAN  95 

reluctance  lies  in  the  specializing  tendencies  of  our  time.  Those 
who  devote  all  their  working  energy  as  loyal  sons  of  our  analyzing 
period  of  science  to  the  minute  detail  of  research  come  easily  into  the 
habit  of  a  nervous  fear  with  regard  to  any  wider  general  outlook.  The 
man  of  research  sees  too  often  how  ignorance  hides  itself  behind  gen- 
eralities. He  knows  too  well  how  much  easier  it  is  to  formulate  vague 
generalities  than  to  contribute  a  new  fact  to  human  knowledge,  and 
how  often  untrained  youngsters  succeed  with  popular  text-books 
which  are  rightly  forgotten  the  next  day.  Methodical  science  must 
thus  almost  encourage  this  aversion  to  any  deviation  from  the  path 
of  painstaking  speciahstic  labor.  Then,  of  course,  it  seems  almost 
a  scientific  duty  to  declare  war  against  an  undertaking  which  ex- 
plicitly asks  everywhere  for  the  wide  perspectives  and  the  last  prin- 
ciples, and  does  not  aim  at  adding  at  this  moment  to  the  mere  treasury 
of  information. 

But  such  a  view  is  utterly  one-sided,  and  to  fight  against  such  one- 
sidedness  and  to  overcome  the  speciahzing  narrowness  of  the  scat- 
tered sciences  was  the  one  central  idea  of  the  plan.  If  there  existed 
no  scholars  who  despise  the  philosophizing  connection,  there  would 
have  hardly  been  any  need  for  this  whole  undertaking;  but  to  yield 
to  such  philosophy-phobia  means  to  declare  the  analytic  movement 
of  science  permanent,  and  to  postpone  a  synthetic  movement  in- 
definitely. Our  time  has  just  to  emphasize,  and  the  leaders  of  thought 
daily  emphasize  it  more,  that  a  mere  heaping  up  of  information  can 
be  merely  a  preparation  for  knowledge,  and  that  the  final  aim  is 
a  Weltanschauung,  a  unified  view  of  the  whole  of  reality.  All  that 
our  Congress  had  to  secure  was  thus  merely  that  the  generalizing  dis- 
cussion of  principles  should  not  be  left  to  men  who  generalized  be- 
cause they  lacked  the  substantial  knowledge  which  is  necessary  to 
specialize.  The  thinkers  we  needed  were  those  who  through  special- 
istic  work  were  themselves  led  to  a  point  where  the  discussion  of  gen- 
eral principles  becomes  unavoidable.  Our  plan  was  by  no  means 
antagonistic  to  the  patient  labors  of  analysis;  the  aim  was  merely  to 
overcome  its  one-sidedness  and  to  stimulate  the  synthesis  as  a  neces- 
sary supplement. 

But  the  objections  against  a  generalizing  plan  were  not  confined  to 
the  mistaken  fear  that  we  sought  to  antagonize  the  productive  work 
of  the  specialist.  They  not  seldom  took  the  form  of  a  general  aver- 
sion to  the  logical  side  of  the  ground-plan.  It  was  often  said  that  such 
a  scheme  has  after  all  interest  only  for  the  logician,  for  whom  science 
as  such  is  an  object  of  study,  and  who  must  thus  indeed  classify  the 
sciences  and  determine  their  logical  relation.  The  real  scientist,  it 
was  said,  does  not  care  for  such  methodological  operations,  and  should 
be  suspicious  from  the  first  of  such  philosophical  high-handedness. 
The  scientist  cannot  forget  how  often  in  the  history  of  civilization 


96         THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

science  was  the  loser  when  it  trusted  its  problems  to  the  metaphy- 
sical thinker  who  substituted  his  lofty  speculations  for  the  hard 
work  of  the  investigator.  The  true  scholar  will  thus  not  only  object 
to  generalizing  "  commonplaces"  as  against  solid  information,  but  he 
will  object  as  well  to  logical  demarcation  lines  and  systematization 
as  against  the  practical  scientific  work  which  does  not  want  to  be 
hampered  by  such  philosophical  subtleties.  Yet  all  these  fears  and 
suspicions  were  still  more  mistaken. 

Nothing  was  further  from  our  intentions  than  a  substitution  of 
metaphysics  for  concrete  science.  It  was  not  by  chance  that  we  took 
such  pains  to  find  the  best  specialists  for  every  section.  No  one  was 
invited  to  enter  into  logical  discussions  and  to  consider  the  relations 
of  science  merely  from  a  dialectic  point  of  view.  The  topic  was  every- 
where the  whole  living  manifoldness  of  actual  relations,  and  the  logi- 
cian had  nothing  else  to  do  than  to  prepare  the  programme.  The 
outlines  of  the  programme  demanded,  of  course,  a  certain  logical 
scheme.  If  hundreds  of  sciences  are  to  take  part,  they  have  to  be 
grouped  somehow,  if  a  merely  alphabetical  order  is  not  adopted;  and 
even  if  we  were  to  proceed  alphabetically,  we  should  have  to  decide 
beforehand  what  part  of  knowledge  is  to  be  recognized  as  a  special 
science.  But  the  logical  order  of  the  ground-plan  refers,  of  course, 
merely  to  the  simple  relation  of  coordination,  subordination,  and 
superordination,  and  the  logician  is  satisfied  with  such  a  classification. 
But  the  endless  variety  of  internal  relations  is  no  longer  to  be  dealt 
with  from  the  point  of  view  of  mere  logic.  We  may  work  out  the 
ground-plan  in  such  a  way  that  we  understand  that  logically  zoology 
is  coordinated  to  botany  and  subordinated  to  mechanics  and  super- 
ordinated  to  ichthyology;  but  this  minimum  of  determination  gives, 
of  course,  not  even  a  hint  of  that  world  of  relations  which  exists  from 
the  standpoint  of  the  biologist  between  the  science  of  zoology  and 
the  science  of  botany,  or  between  the  biological  and  the  mechanical 
studies.  To  discuss  these  relations  of  real  scientific  life  is  the  work  of 
the  biologist  and  not  at  all  of  the  logician. 

The  foregoing  answers  also  at  once  an  objection  which  might  seem 
more  justified  at  the  first  glance.  It  has  been  said  that  we  were  under- 
taking the  work  of  bringing  about  a  synthesis  of  scientific  endeavors, 
and  that  we  yet  had  that  synthesis  already  completed  in  the  pro- 
gramme on  which  the  work  was  to  be  based.  The  scholars  to  be  in- 
vited would  be  bound  by  the  programme,  and  would  therefore  have 
no  other  possibility  than  to  say  with  more  words  what  the  programme 
had  settled  beforehand.  The  whole  effort  would  then  seem  determined 
from  the  start  by  the  arbitrariness  of  the  proposed  ground-plan. 
Now  it  cannot  be  denied  indeed  that  a  certain  factor  of  arbitrariness 
has  to  enter  into  a  programme.  We  have  already  referred  to  the  fact 
that  some  one  must  decide  beforehand  what  fraction  of  science  is  to  be 


THE   OBJECTIONS  TO   THE   PLAN  97 

acknowledged  as  a  self-dependent  discipline.  If  a  biologist  were  to 
work  out  the  scheme,  he  might  decide  that  the  whole  of  philosophy 
was  just  one  science;  while  the  philosopher  might  claim  a  large  num- 
ber of  sections  for  logic  and  ethics  and  philosophy  of  religion,  and  so 
on.  And  the  philosopher,  on  the  other  hand,  might  treat  the  whole  of 
medicine  as  one  part  in  itself,  while  the  physician  might  hold  that  even 
otology  has  to  be  separated  from  rhinology.  A  certain  subjectivity  of 
standpoint  is  unavoidable,  and  we  know  very  well  that  instead  of  the 
one  hundred  and  twenty-ei'ght  sections  of  our  programme  we  might 
have  been  satisfied  with  half  that  number  or  might  have  indulged  in 
double  that  number.  And  yet  there  was  no  possible  plan  which  would 
have  allowed  us  to  invite  the  speakers  without  defining  beforehand 
the  sectional  field  which  each  was  to  represent.  A  certain  courage  of 
opinion  was  then  necessary,  and  sometimes  also  a  certain  adjustment 
to  external  conditions. 

Quite  similar  was  the  question  of  classification.  Just  as  we  had  to 
take  the  responsibility  for  the  staking-out  of  every  section,  we  had 
also  to  decide  in  favor  of  a  certain  grouping,  if  we  desired  to  organ- 
ize the  Congress  and  not  simply  to  bring  out  haphazard  results.  The 
principles  which  are  sufficient  for  a  mere  directory  would  never  allow 
the  shaping  of  a  programme  which  can  be  the  basis  for  synthetic  work. 
Even  a  university  catalogue  begins  with  a  certain  classification,  and 
yet  no  one  fancies  that  such  catalogue  grouping  inhibits  the  freedom 
of  the  university  lecturer.  It  is  easy  to  say,  as  has  been  said,  that  the 
essential  trait  of  the  scientific  life  of  to-day  is  its  live-and-let-live 
character.  Certainly  it  is.  In  the  regular  work  in  our  libraries  and 
laboratories  the  year  round,  everything  depends  upon  this  demo- 
cratic freedom  in  which  every  one  goes  his  own  way,  hardly  asking 
what  his  neighbor  is  doing.  It  is  that  which  has  made  the  specialistic 
sciences  of  our  day  as  strong  as  they  are.  But  it  has  brought  about  at 
the  same  time  this  extreme  tendency  to  unrelated  specialization  with 
its  discouraging  lack  of  unity;  this  heaping  up  of  information  without 
an  outer  harmonious  view  of  the  world ;  and  if  we  were  really  at  least 
once  to  satisfy  the  desire  for  unity,  then  we  had  not  the  right  to  yield 
fully  to  this  live-and-let-live  tendency.  Therefore  some  principle  of 
grouping  had  to  be  accepted,  and  whatever  principle  had  been  chosen, 
it  would  certainly  have  been  open  to  the  criticism  that  it  was  a  pro- 
duct of  arbitrary  decision,  inasmuch  as  other  principles  might  have 
been  possible. 

A  classification  which  in  itself  expresses  all  the  practical  relations  in 
which  sciences  stand  to  each  other  is,  of  course,  absolutely  impossible. 
A  programme  which  should  try  to  arrange  the  place  of  a  special  disci- 
pline in  such  a  way  that  it  would  become  the  neighbor  of  all  those  other 
sciences  with  which  it  has  internal  relation  is  unthinkable.  On  the 
other  hand,  only  if  we  had  tried  to  construct  a  scheme  of  such  exagger- 


98         THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

ated  ambitions  should  we  have  been  really  guilty  of  anticipating  a 
part  of  that  which  the  specialistic  scholars  were  to  tell  us.  The  Con- 
gress had  to  leave  it  to  the  invited  participants  to  discuss  the  totality 
of  relations  which  practically  exist  between  their  fields  and  others, 
and  the  organizers  confined  themselves  to  that  minimum  of  classifica- 
tion which  just  indicates  the  pure  logical  relations,  a  minimum  which 
every  editor  of  encyclopedic  work  would  be  asked  to  initiate  without 
awakening  suspicions  of  interference  with  the  ideas  of  his  contributors. 

The  only  justified  demand  which  could  be  met  was  that  a  system 
of  division  and  classification  should  be  proposed  which  should  give 
fair  play  to  every  existing  scientific  tendency.  The  minimum  of  classi- 
fication was  to  be  combined  with  the  maximum  of  freedom,  and  to 
secure  that  a  careful  consideration  of  principles  was  indeed  necessary. 
To  bring  logical  order  into  the  sciences  which  stand  out  clearly  with 
traditional  rights  is  not  difficult;  but  the  chances  are  too  great  that 
certain  tendencies  of  thought  might  fail  to  find  recognition  or  might 
be  suppressed  by  scientific  prejudice.  Any  serious  omission  would 
indeed  have  necessarily  inhibited  the  freedom  of  expression.  To 
secure  thus  the  greatest  inner  fullness  of  the  programme,  seemed  in- 
deed the  most  important  task  in  the  elaboration  of  the  ground-plan. 
The  fears  that  we  might  offer  empty  generalization  instead  of  schol- 
arly facts,  or  that  we  might  simply  heap  up  encyclopedic  information 
instead  of  gaining  wide  perspectives,  or  that  we  might  interfere  with 
the  living  connections  of  sciences  by  the  logical  demarcation  lines,  or 
that  we  might  disturb  the  scholar  in  his  freedom  by  determining 
beforehand  his  place  in  the  classification,  —  all  these  fears  and  objec- 
tions, which  were  repeatedly  raised  when  the  plan  was  first  proposed, 
seemed  indeed  unimportant  compared  with  the  fear  that  the  pro- 
gramme might  be  unable  to  include  all  scientific  tendencies  of  the 
time. 

That  would  have  been,  indeed,  the  one  fundamental  mistake,  as  the 
whole  Congress  work  was  planned  in  the  service  of  the  great  synthetic 
movement  which  pervades  the  intellectual  life  of  to-day.  The  under- 
taking would  be  useless  and  even  hindering  if  it  were  not  just  the  newer 
and  deeper  tendencies  that  came  to  most  complete  expression  in  it. 
Everything  depended,  therefore,  upon  the  fullest  possible  representa- 
tion of  scientific  endeavors  in  the  plan.  But  no  one  can  become  aware 
of  this  manifoldness  and  of  the  logical  relations  who  does  not  go  back  to 
the  ultimate  principles  of  the  human  search  for  truth.  We  have,  there- 
fore, to  enter  now  into  a  full  discussion  of  the  principles  which  have 
controlled  the  classification  and  subdivision  of  the  whole  work.  The 
discussion  is  necessarily  in  its  essence  a  philosophical  one,  as  it  was 
earlier  made  plain  that  philosophy  must  lay  out  the  plan,  while  in  the 
realization  of  the  plan  through  concrete  work  the  scientist  alone,  and 
not  the  logician,  has  to  speak.    Yet  here  again  it  may  be  said  that 


THE  DEVELOPMENT  OF  CLASSIFICATION  99 

while  our  discussion  of  principles  in  its  essence  is  logical,  in  another 
respect  it  is  a  merely  historical  account.  The  question  is  not  what 
principles  of  classification  are  to  be  acknowledged  as  valuable  now 
that  the  work  of  the  Congress  lies  behind  us,  but  what  principles  were 
accepted  and  really  led  to  the  organization  of  the  work  in  that  form  in 
which  it  presents  itself  in  the  records  of  the  following  volumes. 


II 

THE   CLASSIFICATION  OF   THE  SCIENCES 

L    The  Development  of  Classification 

The  problem  of  dividing  and  subdividing  the  whole  of  human  know- 
ledge and  of  thus  bringing  order  into  the  manifoldness  of  scientific 
efforts  has  fascinated  the  leading  thinkers  of  all  ages.  It  may  often  be 
difficult  to  say  how  far  the  new  principles  of  classification  themselves 
open  the  way  for  new  scientific  progress  and  how  far  the  great  forward 
movements  of  thought  in  the  special  sciences  have  in  turn  influenced 
the  principles  of  classification.  In  any  case  every  productive  age  has 
demanded  the  expression  of  its  deepest  energy  in  a  new  ordering  of 
human  science.  The  history  of  these  efforts  leads  from  Plato  and 
Aristotle  to  Bacon  and  Locke,  to  Bentham  and  Ampere,  to  Kant  and 
Hegel,  to  Comte  and  Spencer,  to  Wundt  and  Windelband.  And  yet 
we  can  hardly  speak  of  a  real  historical  continuity.  In  a  certain  way 
every  period  took  up  the  problem  anew,  and  the  new  aspects  resulted 
not  only  from  the  development  of  the  sciences  themselves  which  were 
to  be  classified,  but  still  more  from  the  differences  of  logical  interest. 
Sometimes  the  classification  referred  to  the  material,  sometimes  to 
the  method  of  treatment,  sometimes  to  the  mental  energies  involved, 
and  sometimes  to  the  ends  to  be  reached.  The  reference  to  the  mental 
faculties  was  certainly  the  earliest  method  of  bringing  order  into 
human  knowledge,  for  the  distinction  of  the  Platonic  philosophy  be- 
tween dialectics,  physics,  and  ethics  pointed  to  the  threefold  charac- 
ter of  the  mind,  to  reason,  perception,  and  desire;  and  it  was  on  the 
threshold  of  the  modern  time,  again,  when  Bacon  divided  the  intel- 
lectual globe  into  three  large  parts  according  to  three  fundamental 
psychical  faculties:  memory,  imagination,  and  reason.  The  memory 
gives  us  history;  the  imagination,  poetry;  the  reason,  philosophy, 
or  the  sciences.  History  was  further  divided  into  natural  and  civil 
history;  natural  history  into  normal,  abnormal,  and  artificial  phe- 
nomena; civil  history  into  political,  literary,  and  ecclesiastical  history. 
The  field  of  reason  was  subdivided  into  man,  nature,  and  God;  the 
domain  of  man  gives,  first,  civil  philosophy,  parted  off  into  inter- 


100       THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

course^  business,  and  government,  and  secondly,  the  philosophy  of 
humanity,  divided  into  that  of  body  and  of  soul,  wherein  medicine 
and  athletics  belong  to  the  body,  logic  and  ethics  to  the  soul.  Nature, 
on  the  other  hand,  was  divided  into  speculative  and  applied  science, 
—  the  speculative  containing  both  physics  and  metaphysics;  the 
applied,  mechanics  and  magic.  All  this  was  full  of  artificial  con- 
structions, and  yet  still  more  marked  by  deep  insight  into  the  needs 
of  Bacon's  time,  and  not  every  modification  of  later  classifiers  was 
logically  a  step  forward. 

Yet  modern  efforts  had  to  seek  quite  different  methods,  and  the 
energies  which  have  been  most  effective  for  the  ordering  of  knowledge 
in  the  last  decades  spring  unquestionably  from  the  system  of  Comte 
and  his  successors.  He  did  not  aim  at  a  system  of  ramifications;  his 
problem  was  to  show  how  the  fundamental  sciences  depend  on  each 
otiier.  A  series  was  to  be  constructed  in  which  each  member  should 
presuppose  the  foregoing.  The  result  was  a  simplicity  which  is  cer- 
tainly tempting,  but  this  simplicity  was  reached  only  by  an  artificial 
emphasis  which  corresponded  completely  to  the  one-sidedness  of 
naturalistic  thought.  It  was  a  philosophy  of  positivism,  the  back- 
ground for  the  gigantic  work  of  natural  science  and  technique  in  the 
last  two  thirds  of  the  nineteenth  century.  Comte 's  fundamental 
thought  is  that  the  science  of  Morals,  in  which  we  study  human  nature 
for  the  government  of  human  life,  is  dependent  on  sociology.  Socio- 
logy, however,  depends  on  biology;  this  on  chemistry;  this  on 
physics;  this  on  astronomy;  and  this  finally  on  mathematics.  In  this 
way,  all  mental  and  moral  sciences,  history  and  philology,  jurispru- 
dence and  theology,  economics  and  politics,  are  considered  as  socio- 
logical phenomena,  as  dealing  with  functions  of  the  human  being. 
But  as  man  is  a  living  organism,  and  thus  certainly  falls  under 
biology,  all  the  branches  of  knowledge  from  history  to  ethics,  from 
jurisprudence  to  aesthetics,  can  be  nothing  but  subdivisions  of  biology. 
The  living  organism,  on  the  other  hand,  is  merely  one  type  of  the 
physical  bodies  on  earth,  and  biology  is  thus  itself  merely  a  depart- 
ment of  physics.  But  as  the  earthly  bodies  are  merely  a  part  of  the 
cosmic  totality,  physics  is  thus  a  part  of  astronomy;  and  as  the  whole 
universe  is  controlled  by  mathematical  laws,  mathematics  must  be 
superordinated  to  all  sciences. 

But  there  followed  a  time  which  overcame  this  thinly  disguised 
example  of  materialism.  It  was  a  time  when  the  categories  of  the 
ph5^siologist  lost  slightly  in  credit  and  the  categories  of  the  psycho- 
logist won  repute.  This  newer  movement  held  that  it  is  artificial  to 
consider  ethical  and  logical  life,  historic  and  legal  action,  literary  and 
religious  emotions,  merely  as  physiological  functions  of  the  living 
organism.  The  mental  life,  however  necessarily  connected  with  brain 
processes,  has  a  positive  reality  of  its  own.  The  psychical  facts  repre- 


THE  DEVELOPMENT  OF   CLASSIFICATION         101 

sent  a  world  of  phenomena  which  in  its  nature  is  absolutely  different 
from  that  of  material  phenomena,  and,  while  it  is  true  that  every 
ethical  action  and  every  logical  thought  can,  from  the  standpoint  of 
the  biologist,  be  considered  as  a  property  of  matter,  it  is  not  less  true 
that  the  sciences  of  mental  phenomena,  considered  impartially,  form 
a  sphere  of  knowledge  closed  in  itself,  and  must  thus  be  coordinated, 
not  subordinated,  to  the  knowledge  of  the  physical  world.  We  should 
say  thus:  all  knowledge  falls  into  two  classes,  the  physical  sciences 
and  the  mental  sciences.  In  the  circle  of  physical  sciences  we  have  the 
general  sciences,  like  physics  and  chemistry,  the  particular  sciences  of 
special  objects,  like  astronomy,  geology,  mineralogy,  biology,  and  the 
formal  sciences,  like  mathematics.  In  the  circle  of  mental  sciences  we 
have  correspondingly,  as  a  general  science,  psychology,  and  as  the 
particular  sciences  all  those  special  mental  and  moral  sciences  which 
deal  with  man's  inner  life,  like  history  or  jurisprudence,  logic  or  ethics, 
and  aU  the  rest.  Such  a  classification,  which  had  its  philosophical 
defenders  about  twenty  years  ago,  penetrated  the  popular  thought 
as  fully  as  the  positivism  of  the  foregoing  generation,  and  was  cer- 
tainly superior  to  its  materialistic  forerunner. 

Of  course  it  was  not  the  first  time  in  the  history  of  civilization  that 
materialism  was  replaced  by  dualism,  that  biologism  was  replaced  by 
psychologism;  and  it  was  also  not  the  first  time  that  the  development 
of  civilization  led  again  beyond  this  point:  that  is,  led  beyond  the 
psychologizing  period.  There  is  no  doubt  that  our  time  presses 
on,  with  all  its  powerful  internal  energies,  away  from  this  Weltan- 
schauung of  yesterday.  The  materialism  was  anti-philosophic,  the 
psychological  dualism  was  unphilosophic.  To-day  the  philosophical 
movement  has  set  in.  The  one-sidedness  of  the  nineteenth  century 
creed  is  felt  in  the  deeper  thought  all  over  the  world :  popular  move- 
ments and  scholarly  efforts  alike  show  the  signs  of  a  coming  idealism, 
which  has  something  better  and  deeper  to  say  than  merely  that  our 
life  is  a  series  of  causal  phenomena.  Our  time  longs  for  a  new  inter- 
pretation of  reality;  from  the  depths  of  every  science  wherein  for 
decades  philosophizing  was  despised,  the  best  scholars  turn  again  to  a 
discussion  of  fundamental  conceptions  and  general  principles.  Histor- 
ical thinking  begins  again  to  take  the  leadership  which  for  half  a  cen- 
tury belonged  to  naturalistic  thinking;  specialistic  research  demands 
increasingly  from  day  to  day  the  readjustment  toward  higher  unities, 
and  the  technical  progress  which  charmed  the  world  becomes  more 
and  more  simply  a  factor  in  an  ideal  progress.  The  appearance  of  this 
unifying  congress  itself  .is  merely  one  of  a  thousand  symptoms  of 
this  change  appearing  in  our  public  life,  and  if  the  scientific  philo- 
sophy is  producing  to-day  book  upon  book  to  prove  that  the  world 
of  phenomena  must  be  supplemented  by  the  world  of  values,  that 
description  must  yield  to  interpretation,  and  that  explanation  must 


102       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

be  harmonized  with  appreciation:  it  is  but  echoing  in  technical 
terms  the  one  great  emotion  of  our  time. 

This  certainly  does  not  mean  that  any  step  of  the  gigantic  material- 
istic, technical,  and  psychological  development  will  be  reversed,  or 
that  progress  in  any  one  of  these  directions  ought  to  cease.  On  the 
contrary,  no  time  was  ever  more  ready  to  put  its  immense  energies 
into  the  service  of  naturalistic  work;  but  it  does  mean  that  our  time 
recognizes  the  one-sidedness  of  these  movements,  recognizes  that  they 
belong  only  to  one  aspect  of  reality,  and  that  another  aspect  is  pos- 
sible; yes,  that  the  other  aspect  is  that  of  our  immediate  life,  with  its 
purposes  and  its  ideals,  its  historical  relations  and  its  logical  aims. 
The  claim  of  materialism,  that  aU  psychical  facts  are  merely  functions 
of  the  organism,  was  no  argument  against  psychology,  because, 
though  the  biological  view  was  possible,  yet  the  other  aspect  is  cer- 
tainly a  necessary  supplement.  In  the  same  way  it  is  no  argument 
against  the  newer  view  that  all  purposes  and  ideals,  all  historical 
actions  and  logical  thoughts,  can  be  considered  as  psychological  phe- 
nomena. Of  course  we  can  consider  them  as  such,  and  we  must  go  on 
doing  so  in  the  service  of  the  psychological  and  sociological  sciences; 
but  we  ought  not  to  imagine  that  we  have  expressed  and  understood 
the  real  character  of  our  historical  or  moral,  our  logical  or  religious 
life  when  we  have  described  and  explained  it  as  a  series  of  phenomena. 
Its  immediate  reality  expresses  itself  above  all  in  the  fact  that  it  has 
a  meaning,  that  it  is  a  purpose  which  we  want  to  understand,  not  by 
considering  its  causes  and  effects,  but  by  interpreting  its  aims  and 
appreciating  its  ideals. 

We  should  say,  therefore,  to-day  that  it  is  most  interesting  and 
important  for  the  scientist  to  consider  human  life  with  all  its  strivings 
and  creations  from  a  biological,  psychological,  sociological  point  of 
view;  that  is,  to  consider  it  as  a  system  of  causal  phenomena;  and 
many  problems  worthy  of  the  highest  energies  have  still  to  be  solved 
in  these  sciences.  But  that  which  the  jurist  or  the  theologian,  the 
student  of  art  or  of  history,  of  literature  or  of  politics,  of  education  or 
of  morality,  is  dealing  with,  refers  to  the  other  aspect  in  which  inner 
life  is  not  a  phenomenon  but  a  system  of  purposes,  not  to  be  ex- 
plained but  to  be  interpreted,  to  be  approached  not  by  causal  but  by 
teleological  methods.  In  this  case  the  historical  sciences  are  no  longer 
sub-sections  of  psychological  or  of  sociological  sciences;  the  concep- 
tion of  science  is  no  longer  identical  with  the  conception  of  the 
science  of  phenomena.  There  exist  sciences  which  do  not  deal  with 
the  description  or  explanation  of  phenomena  at  all,  but  with  the 
internal  relation  and  connection,  the  interpretation  and  appreciation 
of  purpose.  In  this  way  modern  thought  demands  that  sciences  of 
purpose  be  coordinated  with  sciences  of  phenomena.  Only  if  all  these 
tendencies  of  our  time  are  fully  acknowledged  can  the  outer  frame- 


THE  FOUR  THEORETICAL  DIVISIONS  103 

work  of  our  classification  offer  a  fair  field  to  every  scientific  thought, 
while  a  positivistic  system  would  cripple  the  most  promising  tend- 
encies of  the  twentieth  century. 

2.   The  Four  Theoretical  Divisions 

We  have  first  to  determine  the  underlying  structure  of  the  classifi- 
cation, that  is,  we  have  to  seek  the  chief  Divisions,  of  which  our  plan 
shows  seven;  four  theoretical  and  three  practical  ones.    It  will  be  a 
secondary  task  to  subdivide  them  later  into  the  24  Departments  and 
128  Sections.   We  desire  to  divide  the  whole  of  knowledge  in  a  funda- 
mental way,  and  we  must  therefore  start  with  the  question  of  prin- 
ciple:—  what  is  knowledge?  This  question  belongs  to  epistemology, 
and  thus  falls,  indeed,  into  the  domain  of  philosophy.    The  positivist 
is  easily  inclined  to  substitute  for  the  philosophical  problem  the 
empirical  question:    how  did  that  which  we  call  knowledge  grow 
and  develop  itself  in  our  individual  mind,  or  in  the  mind  of  the 
nations?   The  question  becomes,  then,  of  course,  one  which  must  be 
answered  by  psychology,  by  sociology,  and  perhaps  by  biology.  Such 
genetic  inquiries  are  certainly  very  important,  and  the  problem  of 
how  the  processes  of  judging  and  conceiving  and  thinking  are  pro- 
duced in  the  individual  or  social  consciousness,  and  how  they  are  to 
be  explained  through  physical  and  psychical  causes,  deserves  fullest 
attention.   But  its  solution  cannot  even  help  us  as  regards  the  funda- 
mental problem,  what  we  mean  by  knowledge,  and  what  the  ultimate 
value  of  knowledge  may  be,  and  why  we  seek  it.   This  deeper  logical 
inquiry  must  be  answered  somehow  before  those  genetic  studies  of  the 
psychological  and  the  sociological  positivists  can  claim  any  truth  at 
all,  and  thus  any  value,  for  their  outcome.    To  explain  our  present 
knowledge  genetically  from  its  foregoing  causes  means  merely  to  con- 
nect the  present  experience,  which  we  know,  with  a  past  experience, 
which  we  remember,  or  with  earlier  phenomena  which  we  construct 
on  the  basis  of  theories  and  hypotheses;  but  in  any  case  with  facts 
which  we  value  as  parts  of  our  knowledge  and  which  thus  presuppose 
the  acknowledgment  of  the  value  of  knowledge.    We  cannot  deter- 
mine by  hnking  one  part  of  knowledge  with  another  part  of  know- 
ledge whether  we  have  a  right  to  speak  of  knowledge  at  aU  and  to 
rely  on  it. 

We  can  thus  not  start  from  the  childhood  of  man,  or  from  the  begin- 
ning of  humanity,  or  from  any  other  object  of  knowledge,  but  we 
must  begin  with  the  state  which  logically  precedes  all  knowledge; 
that  is,  with  our  immediate  experience  of  real  life.  Here,  in  the  naive 
experience  in  which  we  do  not  know  ourselves  as  objects  which  we 
perceive,  but  where  we  feel  ourselves  in  our  subjective  attitudes  as 
agents  of  will,  as  personalities,  here  we  find  the  original  reality  not  yet 


104       THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

shaped  and  remoulded  by  scientific  conceptions  and  by  the  demands 
of  knowledge.  And  from  this  basis  of  primary,  naive  reality  we  must 
ask  ourselves  what  we  mean  by  seeking  knowledge,  and  how  this 
demand  of  ours  is  different  from  the  other  activities  in  which  we  work 
out  the  meaning  and  the  ideals  of  our  life. 

One  thing  is  certain,  we  cannot  go  back  to  the  old  dogmatic  stand- 
point, whether  rationalistic  or  sensualistic.  In  both  cases  dogmatism 
took  for  granted  that  there  is  a  real  world  of  things  which  exist  in 
themselves  independent  of  our  subjective  attitudes,  and  that  our 
knowledge  has  to  give  us  a  mirror  picture  of  that  self-dependent 
world.  Sensualism  averred  that  we  get  this  knowledge  through  our 
perceptions;  rationalism,  that  we  get  it  by  reasoning.  The  one  as- 
serted that  experience  gives  us  the  data  which  mere  abstract  reason- 
ing can  never  supply;  the  other  asserted  that  our  knowledge  speaks 
of  necessity  which  no  mere  perception  can  find  out.  Our  modern 
time  has  gone  through  the  school  of  philosophical  criticism,  and  the 
dogmatic  ideas  have  lost  for  us  their  meaning.  We  know  that  the 
world  which  we  think  as  independent  cannot  be  independent  of  the 
forms  of  our  thinking,  and  that  no  science  has  reference  to  any  other 
world  than  the  world  which  is  determined  by  the  categories  of  our 
apperception.  There  cannot  be  anything  more  real  than  the  immedi- 
ate pure  experience,  and  if  we  seek  the  truth  of  knowledge,  we  do  not 
set  out  to  discover  something  which  is  hidden  behind  our  experience, 
but  we  set  out  simply  to  make  something  out  of  our  experience  which 
satisfies  certain  demands.  Our  immediate  experience  does  not  contain 
an  objective  thing  and  a  subjective  picture  of  it,  but  they  are  com- 
pletely one  and  the  same  piece  of  experience.  We  have  the  object  of 
our  immediate  knowledge  not  in  the  double  form  of  an  outer  object 
independent  of  ourselves  and  an  idea  in  us,  but  we  have  it  as  our 
object  there  in  the  practical  world  before  science  for  its  special  pur- 
poses has  broken  up  that  bit  of  reality  into  the  physical  material 
thing  and  the  psychical  content  of  consciousness.  And  if  this  double- 
ness  does  not  hold  for  the  immediate  reality  of  pure  experience,  it 
cannot  enter  through  that  reshaping  and  reconstructing  and  connect- 
ing and  interpreting  of  pure  experience  which  we  call  our  knowledge. 
All  that  science  gives  to  us  is  just  such  an  endlessly  enlarged  expe- 
rience, of  which  every  particle  remains  objective  and  independent, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  not  in  us  as  psychical  individuals,  while  yet  com- 
pletely dependent  upon  the  forms  of  our  subjective  experience.  The 
ideal  of  truth  is  thus  not  to  gain  by  reason  or  by  observation  ideas 
in  ourselves  which  correspond  as  well  as  possible  to  absolute  things, 
but  to  reconstruct  the  given  experience  in  the  service  of  certain 
purposes.  Everything  which  completely  fulfills  the  purposes  of  this 
intentional  reconstruction  is  true. 

What  are  these  purposes?   One  thing  is  clear  from  the  first :  There 


THE  FOUR  THEORETICAL   DIVISIONS  105 

cannot  be  a  purpose  where  there  is  not  a  will.  If  we  come  from  pure 
experience  to  knowledge  by  a  purposive  transformation,  we  must 
acknowledge  the  reality  of  will  in  ourselves,  or  rather,  we  must  find 
ourselves  as  will  in  the  midst  of  pure  experience  before  we  reach  any 
knowledge.  And  so  it  is  indeed.  We  can  abstract  from  all  those  recon- 
structions which  the  sciences  suggest  to  us  and  go  back  to  the  most 
immediate  naive  experience;  but  we  can  never  reach  an  experience 
which  does  not  contain  the  doubleness  of  subject  and  object,  of  will 
and  world.  That  doubleness  has  nothing  whatever  to  do  with  the 
difference  of  physical  and  psychical;  both  the  physical  thing  and  the 
psychical  idea  are  objects.  The  antithesis  is  not  that  between  two 
kinds  of  objects,  since  we  have  seen  that  in  the  immediate  experience 
the  objects  are  not  at  all  split  up  into  the  two  groups  of  material  and 
mental  things;  it  is  rather  the  antithesis  between  the  object  in  its 
undifferentiated  state  on  the  one  side  and  the  subject  in  its  will-atti- 
tude on  the  other  side.  Yes,  even  if  we  speak  of  the  subject  which 
stands  as  a  unity  behind  the  will-attitudes,  we  are  already  reconstruct- 
ing the  real  experience  in  the  interest  of  the  purposes  of  knowledge. 
In  the  immediate  experience,  we  have  the  will-attitudes  themselves, 
and  not  a  subject  which  wills  them. 

If  we  ask  ourselves  finally  what  is  then  the  ultimate  difference 
between  those  two  elements  of  our  pure  experience,  between  the  object 
and  the  will-attitude,  we  stand  before  the  ultimate  data:  we  call  that 
element  which  exists  merely  through  a  reference  to  its  opposite,  the 
object,  and  we  call  that  element  of  our  experience  which  is  complete 
in  itself,  the  attitude  of  the  will.  If  we  experienced  hking  or  dislik- 
ing, affirming  or  denying,  approving  or  disapproving  in  the  same  way 
in  which  we  experience  the  red  and  the  green,  the  sweet  and  the  sour, 
the  rock  and  the  tree  and  the  moon,  we  should  know  objects  only. 
But  we  do  experience  them  in  quite  a  different  way.  The  rock  and 
the  tree  do  not  point  to  anything  else,  but  the  approval  has  no  real- 
ity if  it  does  not  point  to  its  opposition  in  disapproval,  and  the  denial 
has  no  meaning  if  it  is  not  meant  in  relation  to  the  affirmative.  This 
doubleness  of  our  primary  experience,  this  having  of  objects  and  of 
antagonistic  attitudes  must  be  acknowledged  wherever  we  speak  of  ex- 
perience at  all.  We  know  no  object  without  attitude,  and  no  attitude 
without  object.  The  two  are  one  state;  object  and  attitude  form 
a  unity  which  we  resolve  by  the  different  way  in  which  we  experience 
these  two  features  of  the  one  state:  we  find  the  object  and  we  live 
through  the  attitude.  It  is  a  different  kind  of  awareness,  the  having 
of  the  object  and  the  taking  of  the  attitude.  In  real  life  our  will  is 
never  an  object  which  we  simply  perceive.  The  psychologist  may  treat 
the  will  as  such,  but  in  the  immediate  experience  of  real  life,  we  are 
certain  of  our  action  by  doing  it  and  not  by  perceiving  our  doing;  and 
this  our  performing  and  rejecting  is  really  our  self  which  we  posit  as 


106       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF  THE   CONGRESS 

absolute  reality,  not  by  knowing  it,  but  by  willing  it.  This  corner- 
stone of  the  Fichtean  philosophy  was  forgotten  throughout  the  un- 
critical and  unphilosophical  decades  of  a  mere  naturalistic  age.  But 
our  time  has  finally  come  to  give  attention  to  it  again. 

Our  pure  experience  thus  contains  will-attitudes  and  objects  of  will, 
and  the  different  attitudes  of  the  will  give  the  fundamental  classes  of 
human  activity.  We  can  easily  recognize  four  different  types  of  will- 
relation  towards  the  world.  Our  will  submits  itself  to  the  world;  our 
will  approves  the  world  as  it  is;  our  will  approves  the  changes  in  the 
world;  our  will  transcends  the  world.  Yet  we  must  make  at  once  one 
more  most  important  discrimination.  We  have  up  to  this  point  sim- 
plified our  pure  experience  too  much.  It  is  not  true  that  we  experience 
only  objects  and  our  own  will-attitudes.  Our  will  reaches  out  not  only 
to  objects,  but  also  to  other  subjects.  In  our  most  immediate  experi- 
ence, not  reshaped  at  all  by  theoretical  science,  our  will  is  in  agree- 
ment or  disagreement  with  other  wills;  tries  to  influence  them,  and 
receives  influences  and  suggestions  from  them.  The  pseudo-philo- 
sophy of  naturalism  must  say  of  course  that  the  will  does  not  stand  in 
any  direct  relation  to  another  will,  but  that  the  other  persons  are  for 
us  simply  material  objects  which  we  perceive,  like  other  objects,  and 
into  which  we  project  mental  phenomena  like  those  which  we  flnd  in 
ourselves 'by  the  mere  conclusion  of  analogy.  But  the  complex  recon- 
structions of  physiological  psychology  are  therein  substituted  for  the 
primary  experience.  If  we  have  to  express  the  agreement  or  disagree- 
ment of  wills  in  the  terms  of  causal  science,  we  may  indeed  be  obliged 
to  transform  the  real  experience  into  such  artificial  constructions; 
but  in  our  immediate  consciousness,  and  thus  at  the  starting-point  of 
our  theory  of  knowledge,  we  have  certainly  to  acknowledge  that  we 
understand  the  other  person,  accept  or  do  not  accept  his  suggestion, 
agree  or  disagree  with  him,  before  we  know  anything  of  a  difference 
between  physical  and  mental  objects. 

We  cannot  agree  with  an  object.  We  agree  directly  with  a  will, 
which  does  not  come  to  us  as  a  foreign  phenomenon,  but  as  a  proposi- 
tion which  we  accept  or  decline.  In  our  immediate  experience  will 
thus  reaches  will,  and  we  are  aware  of  the  difference  between  our  will- 
attitude  as  merely  individual  and  our  will-attitude  as  act  of  agree- 
ment with  the  will-attitude  of  other  individuals.  We  can  go  still 
further.  The  circle  of  other  individuals  whose  will  we  express  in  our 
own  will-act  may  be  narrow  or  wide,  may  be  our  friends  or  the  nation, 
and  this  relation  clearly  constitutes  the  historical  significance  of  our 
attitude.  In  the  one  case  our  act  is  a  merely  personal  choice  for 
personal  purposes  without  any  general  meaning;  in  the  other  case  it 
is  the  expression  of  general  tendencies  and  historical  movements.  Yet 
our  will-decisions  can  have  connections  still  wider  than  those  with  our 
social  community  or  our  nation,  or  even  with  all  living  men  of  to-day. 


THE  FOUR  THEORETICAL  DIVISIONS  107 

It  can  seek  a  relation  to  the  totality  of  those  whom  we  aim  to  acknow- 
ledge as  real  subjects.  It  thus  becomes  independent  of  the  chance 
experience  of  this  or  that  man,  or  this  or  that  movement,  which 
appeals  to  us,  but  involves  in  an  independent  way  the  reference  to 
every  one  who  is  to  be  acknowledged  as  a  subject  at  all.  Such  refer- 
ence, which  is  no  longer  bound  to  any  special  group  of  historical  in- 
dividuals, thus  becomes  strictly  over-individual.  We  can  then  dis- 
criminate three  stages:  our  merely  individual  wiU;  secondly,  our  will 
as  bound  by  other  historical  individuals;  and  thirdly,  our  over- 
individual  will,  which  is  not  influenced  by  any  special  individual, 
but  by  the  general  demands  for  the  idea  of  a  personality. 

Each  of  those  four  great  types  of  will-attitude  which  we  insisted  on 
—  that  is,  of  submitting,  of  approving  the  given,  of  approving  change, 
and  of  transcending  —  can  be  carried  out  on  these  three  stages,  that 
is,  as  individual  act,  as  historical  act,  and  as  over-individual  act. 
And  we  may  say  at  once  that  only  if  we  submit  and  approve  and 
change  and  transcend  in  an  over-individual  act,  do  we  have  Truth 
and  Beauty  and  Morality  and  Conviction.  If  we  approve,  for  instance, 
a  given  experience  in  an  individual  will-act,  we  have  simply  personal 
enjoyment  and  its  object  is  simply  agreeable;  if  we  approve  it  in  har- 
mony with  other  individuals,  we  reach  a  higher  attitude,  yet  one  which 
cannot  claim  absolute  value,  as  it  is  dependent  on  historical  considera- 
tions and  on  the  tastes  and  desires  of  a  special  group  or  a  school  or  a 
nation  or  an  age.  But  if  we  approve  the  given  object  just  as  it  is  in  an 
over-individual  will-act,  then  we  have  before  us  a  thing  of  beauty, 
whose  value  is  not  dependent  upon  our  personal  enjoyment  as  indi- 
viduals, but  is  demanded  as  a  joy  forever,  by  every  one  whom  we 
acknowledge  at  all  as  a  complete  subject.  In  exactly  the  same  way, 
we  may  approve  a  change  in  the  world  from  any  individual  point  of 
view:  we  have  then  to  do  with  technical,  practical  achievements;  or 
we  may  approve  it  in  agreement  with  others:  we  then  enter  into  the 
historical  interests  of  our  time.  Or  we  may  approve  it,  finally,  in  an 
over-individual  way,  without  any  reference  to  any  special  person- 
ality: then  only  is  it  valuable  for  all  time,  then  only  is  it  morally  good. 
And  if  our  will  is  transcending  experience  in  an  individual  way,  it  can 
again  claim  no  more  than  a  subjective  satisfaction  furnished  by  any 
superstition  or  hope.  But  if  the  transcending  will  is  over-individual, 
it  reaches  the  absolute  values  of  religion  and  metaphysics. 

Exactly  the  same  differences,  finally,  must  occur  when  our  will  sub- 
mits itself  to  experience.  This  submission  may  be,  again,  an  individ- 
ual decision  for  individual  purposes;  no  absolute  value  belongs  to  it. 
Or  it  may  be  again  a  yielding  to  the  suggestions  of  other  individuals; 
or  it  may,  finally,  again  be  an  over-individual  submission,  which  seeks 
no  longer  a  personal  interest.  This  submission  is  not  to  the  authority 
of  others,  and  is  without  reference  to  any  individual;   we  assume 


108       THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

that  every  one  who  is  to  share  with  us  our  world  of  experience  has  to 
share  this  submission  too.  That  alone  is  a  submission  to  truth,  and 
experience,  considered  in  so  far  as  we  submit  ourselves  to  it  over- 
individually,  constitutes  our  knowledge. 

The  system  of  knowledge  is  thus  the  system  of  experience  with  all 
that  is  involved  in  it  in  so  far  as  it  demands  submission  from  our  over- 
individual  will,  and  the  classification  which  we  are  seeking  must  be 
thus  a  division  and  subdivision  of  our  over-individual  submissions. 
But  the  submission  itself  can  be  of  very  different  characters  and  these 
various  types  must  give  the  deepest  logical  principles  of  scientific 
classification.  To  point  at  once  to  the  fundamental  differences:  our 
will  acknowledges  the  demands  of  other  wills  and  of  objects.  We  can- 
not live  our  life  —  and  this  is  not  meant  in  a  biological  sense,  but, 
first  of  all,  in  a  teleological  sense  —  our  life  becomes  meaningless,  if 
our  will  does  not  respect  the  reality  of  will-demands  and  of  objects  of 
will.  Now  we  have  seen  that  the  will  which  demands  our  decision  may 
be  either  the  individual  will  of  other  subjects  or  the  over-individual 
will,  which  belongs  to  every  subject  as  such  and  is  independent  of  any 
individuality.  We  can  say  at  once  that  in  the  same  way  we  are  led  to 
acknowledge  that  the  object  has  partly  an  over-individual  character, 
that  is,  necessarily  belongs  to  the  world  of  objects  of  every  possible 
subject,  and  partly  an  individual  character,  as  our  personal  object. 
We  have  thus  four  large  groups  of  experiences  to  which  we  submit 
ourselves:  over-individual  will-acts,  individual  will-acts,  over-indi- 
vidual objects,  individual  objects.  They  constitute  the  first  four  large 
divisions  of  our  system. 

The  over-individual  will-acts,  which  are  as  such  teleologically  bind- 
ing for  every  subject  and  therefore  norms  for  his  will,  give  us  the 
Normative  Sciences.  The  individual  will-acts  in  the  world  of  historical 
manifoldness  give  us  the  Historical  Sciences.  The  objects,  in  so  far 
as  they  belong  to  every  individual,  make  up  the  physical  world,  and 
thus  give  us  the  Physical  Sciences;  and  finally  the  objects,  in  so  far 
as  they  belong  to  the  individual,  are  the  contents  of  consciousness, 
and  thus  give  us  the  Mental  Sciences.  We  have  then  the  demarca- 
tion lines  of  our  first  four  large  divisions :  the  Normative,  the  Histor- 
ical, the  Physical,  and  the  Mental  Sciences.  Yet  their  meaning  and 
method  and  difference  must  be  characterized  more  fully.  We  must 
understand  why  we  have  here  to  deal  with  four  absolutely  different 
types  of  scientific  systems,  why  the  over-individual  objects  lead  us 
to  general  laws  and  to  the  determination  of  the  future,  while  the  study 
of  the  individual  will-acts,  for  instance,  gives  us  the  system  of  history, 
which  turns  merely  to  the  past  and  does  not  seek  natural  laws;  and 
why  the  study  of  the  norms  gives  us  another  kind  of  system  in  which 
neither  a  causal  nor  an  historical,  but  a  purely  logical  connection  pre- 
vails. Yet  all  these  methodological  differences  result  necessarily  from 


THE  PHYSICAL  AND   THE  MENTAL  SCIENCES     109 

the  material  with  which  these  four  different  groups  of  sciences  are 
working. 

Let  us  start  again  from  the  consideration  of  our  original  logical 
purpose.  We  feel  ourselves  bound  and  limited  in  our  will  by  physical 
things,  by  psychical  contents,  by  the  demands  of  other  subjects,  and 
by  norms.  The  purpose  of  all  our  knowledge  is  to  develop  completely 
all  that  is  involved  in  this  bondage.  We  want  to  develop  in  an  over- 
individual  way  all  the  obligations  for  our  submission  which  are 
necessarily  included  in  the  given  objects  and  the  given  demands  of 
subjects.  We  start  of  course  everywhere  and  in  every  direction  from 
the  actual  experience,  but  we  expand  the  experience  by  seeking  those 
objects  and  those  demands  to  which,  as  necessarily  following  from  the 
immediately  given  experience,  we  must  also  submit.  And  in  thus 
developing  the  whole  system  of  submissions,  the  interpretation  of 
the  experience  itself  becomes  transformed:  the  physicist  may  per- 
haps substitute  imperceptible  atoms  for  the  physical  object  and  the 
psychologist  may  substitute  sensations  for  the  real  idea,  and  the 
historian  may  substitute  combinations  of  influences  for  the  real  per- 
sonality, and  the  student  of  norms  may  substitute  combinations  of 
conflicting  demands  for  the  one  complete  duty;  yet  in  every  case  the 
substitution  is  logically  necessary  and  furnishes  us  what  we  call  truth 
inasmuch  as  it  is  needed  to  develop  the  concrete  system  of  our  sub- 
missions and  thus  to  express  our  confidence  in  the  order-lines  of  real- 
ity. And  each  of  these  substitutions  and  supplementations  becomes, 
as  material  of  knowledge,  itself  a  part  of  the  world  of  experience. 

3.    The  Physical  and  the  Mental  Sciences 

The  physicist,  we  said,  speaks  of  the  world  of  objects  in  so  far  as 
they  belong  to  every  possible  subject,  and  are  material  for  a  merely 
passive  spectator.  Of  course  the  pure  experience  does  not  offer  us  any- 
thing of  that  kind.  We  insisted  that  the  objects  of  our  real  life  are 
objects  of  our  will  and  of  our  attitudes,  and  are  at  the  same  time  un- 
differentiated into  the  physical  things  outside  of  us  and  the  psychical 
ideas  in  us.  To  reach  the  abstraction  of  the  physicist,  we  have  thus  to 
cut  loose  the  objects  from  our  will  and  to  separate  the  over-individual 
elements  from  the  individual  elements.  Both  transformations  are 
clearly  demanded  by  our  logical  aims.  As  to  the  cutting  loose  from  our 
will,  it  means  considering  the  object  as  if  it  existed  for  itself,  as  if  it 
were  a  mere  passively  given  material  and  not  a  material  of  our  per- 
sonal interests.  But  just  that  is  needed.  We  want  to  find  out  how 
far  we  have  to  submit  ourselves  to  the  object.  If  we  want  to  live  our 
life,  we  must  adjust  our  attitudes  to  things,  and,  as  we  know  our  will, 
we  must  seek  to  understand  the  other  factor  in  the  complex  experi- 
ence, the  object  of  our  will,  and  we  must  find  out  what  it  involves  in 


110       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

itself.  But  we  do  not  understand  the  object  and  the  submission  which 
it  demands  if  we  do  not  completely  understand  its  relation  to  our 
desires.  Our  total  submission  to  the  thing  thus  involves  our  acknow- 
ledgment of  aU  that  we  have  to  expect  from  it.  And  although  the 
real  experience  is  a  unity  of  will  and  thing,  we  have  thus  the  most 
immediate  interest  in  considering  what  we  have  to  expect  from  the 
thing  in  itself,  without  reference  to  our  will.  That  means  finding  out 
the  effects  of  the  given  object  with  a  subject  as  the  passive  spec- 
tator. We  eliminate  artificially,  therefore,  the  activity  of  the  subject 
and  construct  as  presupposition  for  this  circle  of  knowledge  a  nowhere 
existing  subject  without  activity,  for  which  the  thing  exists  merely 
as  a  cause  of  the  effects  which  it  produces. 

The  first  step  towards  natural  science  is,  therefore,  to  dissolve 
the  real  experience  into  thing  and  personality;  that  is,  into  object 
and  active  subject,  and  to  eliminate  in  an  artificial  abstraction  the 
activity  of  the  subject,  making  the  object  material  of  merely  passive 
awareness,  and  related  no  longer  to  the  will  but  merely  to  other 
objects.  It  may  be  more  difficult  to  understand  the  second  step  which 
naturalism  has  to  take  before  a  natural  science  is  possible.  It  must 
dissolve  the  object  of  will  into  an  over-individual  and  an  individual 
part  and  must  eliminate  the  individual.  That  part  of  my  objects 
which  belongs  to  me  alone  is  their  psychical  side;  that  which  belongs 
to  all  of  us  and  is  the  object  of  ever  new  experience  is  the  physical 
object.  As  a  physicist,  in  the  widest  sense  of  the  word,  I  have  to  ignore 
the  objects  in  so  far  as  they  are  my  ideas  and  have  to  consider  the 
stones  and  the  stars,  the  inorganic  and  the  organic  objects,  as  they 
are  outside  of  me,  material  for  every  one.  The  logical  purpose  of  this 
second  abstraction  may  be  perhaps  formulated  in  the  following  way. 

We  have  seen  that  the  purpose  of  the  study  of  the  objects  is  to  find 
out  what  we  have  to  expect  from  them;  that  is,  to  what  effects  of  the 
given  thing  we  have  to  submit  ourselves  in  anticipation.  The  ideal 
aim  is  thus  to  understand  completely  how  present  objects  and  future 
objects  —  that  is,  how  causes  and  effects  —  are  connected.  The  first 
stage  in  such  knowledge  of  causal  connections  is,  of  course,  the  obser- 
vation of  empirical  consequences.  Our  feeling  of  expectation  grows 
with  the  regularity  of  observed  succession;  yet  the  ideal  aim  can 
never  be  fulfilled  in  that  way.  The  mere  observation  of  regularities 
can  help  us  to  reduce  a  particular  case  to  a  frequently  observed  type, 
but  what  we  seek  to  understand  is  the  necessity  of  the  process.  Of 
course  we  have  to  formulate  laws,  and  as  soon  as  we  acknowledge 
a  special  law  to  be  expressive  of  a  necessity,  the  subsumption  of  the 
particular  case  under  the  law  will  satisfy  us  even  if  the  necessity  of  the 
connection  is  not  recognized  in  the  particular  case.  We  are  satisfied 
because  the  acknowledgment  of  the  law  involved  all  possible  cases. 
But  we  do  not  at  all  feel  that  we  have  furnished  a  real  explanation  if 


THE  PHYSICAL  AND  THE  MENTAL   SCIENCES     111 

the  law  means  to  us  merely  a  generalization  of  routine  experiences, 
and  if  thus  no  absolute  validity  is  attached  to  the  law.  This  necessity 
between  cause  and  effect  must  thus  have  its  ultimate  reason  in  our 
own  understanding.  We  must  be  logically  obliged  to  connect  the 
objects  in  such  a  way,  and  wherever  observation  seems  to  contradict 
that  which  is  logically  necessary,  we  must  reshape  our  idea  of  the 
object  till  the  demands  of  reason  are  fulfilled.  That  is,  we  must  sub- 
stitute for  the  given  object  an  abstraction  which  serves  the  purpose  of 
a  logically  necessary  connection.  That  demand  is  clearly  not  satisfied 
if  we  simply  group  the  totality  of  such  causal  judgments  under  the 
single  name.  Causality,  and  designate  thus  all  these  judgments  as 
results  of  a  special  disposition  of  the  understanding.  We  never  under- 
stand why  just  this  cause  demands  just  this  effect  so  long  as  we  rely 
on  such  vague  and  mystical  power  of  our  reason  to  link  the  world  by 
causality. 

But  the  situation  changes  at  once  if  we  go  still  further  back  in  the 
categories  of  our  understanding.  While  a  mere  demand  for  causality 
never  explains  what  cause  is  to  be  linked  with  what  effect,  the  vague- 
ness disappears  when  we  understand  this  demand  for  causality  itself 
as  the  product  of  a  more  fundamental  demand  for  identity.  That  an 
object  remains  identical  with  itself  does  not  need  for  us  any  further 
interpretation.  That  is  the  ultimate  presupposition  of  our  thought, 
and  where  a  complete  identity  is  found  nothing  demands  further 
explanation.  All  scientific  effort  aims  at  so  rethinking  different  ex- 
periences that  they  can  be  regarded  as  partially  identical,  and  every 
discovery  of  necessary  connection  is  ultimately  a  demonstration  of 
identity.  If  we  seek  connections  with  the  final  aim  to  understand 
them  as  necessary,  we  must  conceive  the  world  of  our  objects  in  such 
a  way  that  it  is  possible  to  consider  the  successive  experiences  as  parts 
of  a  self-identical  world;  that  is,  as  parts  of  a  world  in  which  no  sub- 
stance and  no  energy  can  disappear  or  appear  anew.  To  reach  this  end 
it  is  obviously  needed  that  we  eliminate  from  the  world  of  objects  all 
that  cannot  be  conceived  as  identically  returning  in  a  new  experience; 
that  is,  all  that  belongs  to  the  present  experience  only.  We  do  elimin- 
ate this  by  taking  it  up  conceptually  into  the  subject  and  calling  it 
psychical,  and  thus  leaving  to  the  object  merely  that  which  is  con- 
ceived as  belonging  to  the  world  of  everybody's  experience,  that  is,  of 
over-individual  experience.  The  whole  history  of  natural  science  is 
first  of  all  the  gigantic  development  of  this  transformation,  resolution, 
and  reconstruction.  The  objects  of  experience  are  re-thought  till 
everything  is  eliminated  which  cannot  be  conceived  as  identical  with 
itself  in  the  experiences  of  all  iadividuals  and  thus  as  belonging  to  the 
over-individual  world.  All  the  substitutions  of  atoms  for  the  real  thing, 
and  of  energies  for  the  real  changes,  are  merely  conceptional  schemes 
to  satisfy  this  demand. 


112       THE   SCIENTIFIC   PLAN  OF   THE   CONGRESS 

The  logically  primary  step  is  thus  not  the  separation  of  the  physical 
and  the  psychical  things  plus  the  secondary  demand  to  connect  the 
physical  things  causally;  the  order  is  exactly  opposite.  The  primary 
desire  is  to  connect  the  real  objects  and  to  understand  them  as  causes 
and  effects.  This  understanding  demands  not  only  empirical  observa- 
tion, but  insight  into  the  necessary  connection.  Necessary  connec- 
tion, on  the  other  hand,  exists  merely  for  identical  objects  and  identi- 
cal qualities.  But  in  the  various  experiences  only  that  is  identical 
which  is  independent  of  the  momentary  individual  experiences,  and 
therefore  we  need  as  the  ultimate  aim  a  reconstruction  of  the  object 
into  the  two  parts,  the  one  perceptional,  which  refers  to  our  individual 
experience  5  and  the  other  conceptional,  which  expresses  that  which 
can  be  conceived  as  identical  in  every  new  experience.  The  ideal  of 
this  constructed  world  is  the  mechanical  universe  in  which  every 
atom  moves  by  causal  necessity  because  there  is  nothing  in  that 
universe,  no  element  of  substance  and  no  element  of  energy,  which 
will  not  remain  identical  in  all  changes  of  the  universe  which  are  pos- 
sibly to  be  expected.  It  becomes  completely  determinable  by  antici- 
pation and  the  system  of  our  submissions  to  the  object  can  be  com- 
pletely'constructed.  The  totality  of  intellectual  efforts  to  reconstruct 
such  a  causally  connected  over-individual  world  of  objects  clearly 
represents  a  unity  of  its  own.    It  is  the  system  of  physical  sciences. 

The  physical  universe  is  thus  not  the  totality  of  our  objects.  It  is  a 
substitution  for  our  real  objects,  constructed  by  eliminating  the  indi- 
vidual parts  of  our  objects  of  experience.  These  individual  parts  are 
the  psychical  aspects  of  our  objective  experience,  and  they  clearly 
awake  our  scientific  interest  too.  The  physical  sciences  need  thus  as 
counterpart  a  division  of  mental  sciences.  Their  aim  must  be  the  same. 
We  want  to  foresee  the  psychical  results  and  to  understand  causally 
the  psychical  experience.  Yet  it  is  clear  that  the  plan  of  the  mental 
sciences  must  be  quite  different  in  principle  from  that  of  the  sciences 
of  nature.  The  causal  connection  of  the  physical  universe  was  ulti- 
mately anchored  in  the  identity  of  the  object  through  various  experi- 
ences; while  the  object  of  experience  was  psychical  for  us  just  in  so 
far  as  it  could  never  be  conceived  as  identical  in  different  phases  of 
reality.  The  psychical  object  is  an  ever  new  creation;  my  idea  can 
never  be  your  idea.  Their  meaning  may  be  identical,  but  the  psych- 
ical stuff,  the  content  of  my  consciousness,  can  never  be  object  for 
any  one  else,  and  even  in  myself  the  idea  of  to-day  is  never  the  idea 
of  yesterday  or  to-morrow.  But  if  there  cannot  be  identity  in  different 
psychical  experiences,  it  is  logically  impossible  to  connect  them 
directly  by  necessity.  If  we  yet  want  to  master  their  successive 
appearance,  we  must  substitute  an  indirect  connection  for  the  direct 
one,  and  must  describe  and  explain  the  psychical  phenomena  through 
reference  to  the  physical  world.   It  is  in  this  way  that  modern  psycho- 


THE  HISTORICAL  AND  THE  NORMATIVE  SCIENCES     113 

logy  has  substituted  elementary  sensations  for  the  real  contents  of 
consciousness  and  has  constructed  relations  between  these  element- 
ary mental  states  on  the  basis  of  processes  in  the  organism,  especially 
brain  processes.  Here,  again,  reality  is  left  behind  and  a  mere  concep- 
tional  construction  is  put  in  its  place.  But  this  construction  fulfills 
its  purpose  and  thus  gives  us  truth;  and  if  the  basis  is  once  given,  the. 
psychological  sciences  can  build  up  a  causal  system  of  the  conscious 
processes  in  the  individual  man  and  in  society. 

4.    The  Historical^  and  the  Normative  Sciences 

The  two  divisions  of  the  physical  and  mental  sciences  represent  our 
systematized  submission  to  objects.  But  we  saw  from  the  first  that  it 
is  an  artificial  abstraction  to  consider  in  our  real  experience  the  object 
alone.  We  saw  clearly  that  we,  as  acting  personalities,  in  our  will  and 
in  our  attitudes,  do  not  feel  ourselves  in  relation  to  objects,  merely,  but 
to  will-acts ;  and  that  these  will-acts  were  the  individual  ones  of  other 
subjects  or  the  over-individual  ones  which  come  to  us  in  our  conscious- 
ness of  norms.  The  sciences  which  deal  with  our  submissions  to  the 
individual  will-acts  of  others  are  the  Historical  Sciences.  Their  start- 
ing-point is  the  same  as  that  of  the  object  sciences,  the  immediate 
experience.  But  the  other  subjects  reach  our  individuality  from  the 
start  in  a  different  way  from  the  objects.  The  wills  of  other  subjects 
come  to  us  as  propositions  with  which  we  have  to  agree  or  disagree ; 
as  suggestions,  which  we  are  to  imitate  or  to  resist;  and  they  carry  in 
themselves  that  reference  to  an  opposite  which,  as  we  saw,  character- 
izes all  will-activity.  The  rock  or  the  tree  in  our  surroundings  may 
stimulate  our  reactions,  but  does  not  claim  to  be  in  itself  a  decision 
with  an  alternative.  But  the  political  or  legal  or  artistic  or  social  or 
religious  will  of  my  neighbors  not  only  demands  my  agreement  or 
disagreement,  but  presents  itself  to  me  in  its  own  meaning  as  a  free 
decision  which  rejects  the  opposite,  and  its  whole  meaning  is  de- 
stroyed if  I  consider  it  like  the  tree  or  the  rock  as  a  mere  phenom- 
enon, as  an  object  in  the  world  of  objects.  Whoever  has  clearly 
understood  that  politics  and  religion  and  knowledge  and  art  and  law 
come  to  me  from  the  first  quite  differently  from  objects,  can  never 
doubt  that  their  systematic  connection  must  be  most  sharply  sepa- 
rated from  all  the  sciences  which  connect  impressions  of  objects,  and 
is  falsified  if  the  historical  disciplines  are  treated  simply  as  parts  of 
the  sciences  of  phenomena  —  for  instance,  as  parts  of  sociology,  the 
science  of  society  as  a  psycho-physical  object. 

Just  as  natural  science  transcends  the  immediately  experienced 
object  and  works  out  the  whole  system  of  our  necessary  submissions 
to  the  world  of  objects,  so  the  historical  sciences  transcend  the  social 
will-acts  which  approach  us  in  our  immediate  experience,  and  again 


114       THE   SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF   THE  CONGRESS 

seek  to  find  what  we  are  really  submitting  to  if  we  accept  the  sugges- 
tions of  our  social  surroundings.  And  yet  this  similar  demand  has 
most  dissimilar  consequences.  We  submit  to  an  object  and  want  to 
find  out  what  we  are  really  submitting  to.  That  cannot  mean  any- 
thing else,  as  we  have  seen,  than  to  seek  the  effects  of  the  object  and 
thus  to  look  forward  to  what  we  have  to  expect  from  the  object. 
On  the  other  hand,  if  we  want  to  find  out  what  we  are  really  sub- 
mitting to  if  we  agree  with  the  decision  of  our  neighbor,  the  only 
meaning  of  the  question  can  be  to  ask  what  our  neighbor  really  is 
deciding  on,  what  is  contained  in  his  decision;  and  as  his  decision 
must  mean  an  agreement  or  disagreeme"ht  with  the  will-act  of  another 
subject,  we  cannot  understand  the  suggestion  which  comes  to  us 
without  understanding  in  respect  to  what  propositions  of  others  it 
takes  a  stand.  Our  interest  is  in  this  case  thus  led  from  those  sub- 
jects of  will  which  enter  into  our  immediate  experience  to  other  sub- 
jects whose  purposes  stand  in  the  relation  of  suggestion  and  demand 
to  the  present  ones.  And  if  we  try  to  develop  the  system  of  these 
relations,  we  come  to  an  endless  chain  of  will-relations,  in  which  one 
individual  will  always  points  back  in  its  decisions  to  another  indi- 
vidual will  with  which  it  agrees  or  disagrees,  which  it  imitates  or 
overcomes  by  a  new  attitude  of  will;  and  the  whole  network  of  these 
will-relations  is  the  political  or  religious  or  artistic  or  social  history 
of  mankind.  This  system  of  history  as  a  system  of  teleologically 
connected  will-attitudes  is  elaborated  from  the  will-propositions 
which  reach  us  in  immediate  experience,  with  the  same  necessity 
with  which  the  mechanical  universe  of  natural  science  is  worked  out 
from  the  objects  of  our  immediate  experience. 

The  historical  system  of  will-connections  is  similar  to  the  system  of 
object-connections,  not  only  in  its  starting  in  the  immediate  experi- 
ence, but  further  in  its  also  seeking  identities.  Without  this  feature 
history  would  not  offer  to  our  understanding  real  connections.  We 
must  link  the  will-attitudes  of  men  by  showing  the  identity  of  the 
alternatives.  Just  as  the  physical  thing  is  substituted  by  a  large 
number  of  atoms  which  remain  identical  in  the  causal  changes,  in 
the  same  way  the  personality  is  substituted  by  an  endless  manifold- 
ness  of  decisions  and  becomes  linked  with  the  historical  community 
by  the  thought  that  each  of  these  partial  decisions  refers  to  an  alter- 
native which  is  identical  with  that  of  other  persons.  And  yet  there 
remains  a  most  essential  difference  between  the  historical  and  the 
causal  connection.  In  a  world  of  things  the  mere  identical  continu- 
ity is  sufficient  to  determine  the  phenomena  of  any  given  moment. 
In  a  world  of  wiU  the  identity  of  alternatives  cannot  determine  be- 
forehand the  actual  decision ;  that  belongs  to  the  free  activity  of  the 
subject.  If  this  factor  of  freedom  were  left  out,  man  would  be  made 
an  object  and  history  a  mere  appendix  of  natural  science.    The 


THE  HISTORICAL  AND  THE  NORMATIVE  SCIENCES     115 

connection  of  the  historian  can  therefore  never  be  a  necessary  one, 
however  much  we  may  observe  empirical  regularities.  If  there  were 
no  identities,  our  reason  could  not  find  connection  in  history;  but  if  the 
historical  connections  were  necessary,  like  the  causal  ones,  it  would 
not  be  history.  The  historian  is,  therefore,  unable  and  without  the 
ambitien  to  look  into  the  future  like  the  naturalist;  his  domain  is 
the  past. 

Yet  will-attitudes  and  will-acts  can  also  be  brought  into  necessary 
connection;  that  is,  we  can  conceive  will-acts  as  teleologically  iden- 
tical with  each  other  and  exempt  from  the  freedom  of  the  individual. 
That  is  clearly  possible  only  if  they  are  conceived  as  beyond  the  free- 
dom of  individual  decision  and  related  to  the  over-individual  subject. 
The  question  is  then  no  longer  how  this  special  man  wills  and  decides, 
but  how  far  a  certain  will-decision  binds  every  possible  individual  who 
performs  this  act  if  he  is  to  share  our  common  world  of  will  and  mean- 
ing. Such  an  over-individual  connection  of  will-acts  is  what  we  call 
the  logical  connection.  It  shares  with  all  other  connections  the  depend- 
ence upon  the  category  of  identity.  The  logical  connection  shows 
how  far  one  act  or  combination  of  acts  involves,  and  thus  is  partially 
identical  with,  a  new  combination.  This  logical  connection  has,  in 
common  with  the  causal  connection,  necessity;  and  in  common  with 
the  historical  connection,  teleological  character.  Any  individual  will- 
act  of  historical  life  may  be  treated  for  certain  purposes  as  such  a 
starting-point  of  over-individual  relations;  it  would  then  lead  to  that 
scientific  treatment  which  gives  us  an  interpretation,  for  instance,  of 
law.  Such  interpretative  sciences  belong  to  the  system  of  history  in 
the  widest  sense  of  the  word. 

The  chief  interest,  however,  must  belong  to  the  logical  connections 
of  those  will-acts  which  themselves  have  over-individual  character. 
A  merely  individual  proposition  can  lead  to  necessary  logical  connec- 
tion, but  cannot  claim  that  scientific  importance  which  belongs  to 
the  logical  connection  of  those  propositions  which  are  necessary  for 
the  constitution  of  every  real  experience :  the  science  of  chess  cannot 
stand  on  the  same  level  with  the  science  of  geometry,  the  science  of 
local  legal  statutes  not  on  the  same  level  with  the  system  of  ethics. 
The  logical  connections  of  the  over-individual  attitudes  thus  consti- 
tute the  fourth  large  division  besides  the  physical,  the  mental,  and  the 
historical  sciences.  It  must  thus  comprise  the  systems  of  all  those 
propositions  which  are  presuppositions  of  our  common  reality,  in- 
dependent of  the  free  individual  decision.  Here  belong  the  acts  of 
approval  —  the  ethical  approval  of  changes  and  achievements,  as 
weU  as  the  aesthetic  approval  of  the  given  world ;  the  acts  of  convic- 
tion —  the  religious  convictions  of  a  superstructure  of  the  world  as 
well  as  the  metaphysical  convictions  of  a  substructure;  and  above 
all,  the  acts  of  affirmation  and  submission,  the  logical  as  well  as  the 


116       THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF   THE  CONGRESS 

mathematical.  But  to  be  consistent  we  must  really  demand  that 
merely  the  over-individual  logical  connections  are  treated  in  this 
division.  If  we  deal,  for  instance,  with  the  sesthetical  or  ethical  acts  as 
psychological  experiences,  or  as  historical  propositions,  they  belong 
to  the  psychical  or  historical  division.  Only  the  philosophical  system 
of  ethics  or  aesthetics  finds  its  place  in  this  division.  It  is  difficult  to 
find  a  suitable  name  for  this  whole  system  of  logical  connections  of 
over-individual  attitudes.  Perhaps  it  would  be  most  correct  to  call  it 
the  Sciences  of  Values,  inasmuch  as  every  one  of  these  over-individual 
decisions  constitutes  a  value  in  our  world  which  our  individual  will 
finds  as  an  absolute  datum  like  the  objects  of  experience.  Seen  from 
another  point  of  view,  these  values  appear  as  norms  which  bind  our 
practical  will  inasmuch  as  these  absolute  values  demand  of  our  will  to 
realize  them,  and  it  may  thus  be  permitted  to  designate  this  whole 
group  of  sciences  as  a  Division  of  Normative  Sciences. 

Our  logical  explanation  of  the  meaning  of  these  four  divisions 
naturally  began  with  the  interpretation  of  that  science  which  usually 
takes  precedence  in  popular  thought  —  with  the  science  of  nature, 
that  is,  and  passed  then  to  those  groups  whose  methodological  situa- 
tion is  seen  rather  vaguely  by  our  positivistic  age.  But  as  soon  as  we 
have  once  defined  and  worked  out  the  boundary  lines  of  each  of  these 
four  divisions,  it  would  appear  more  logical  to  change  their  order  and 
to  begin  with  that  division  whose  material  is  those  over-individual 
will-acts  on  which  all  possible  knowledge  must  depend,  and  then  to 
turn  to  those  individual  will-acts  which  determine  the  formulation 
of  our  present-day  knowledge,  and  then  only  to  go  to  the  objects  of 
knowledge,  the  over-individual  and  the  individual  ones.  In  short,  we 
must  begin  with  the  normative  sciences,  consider  in  the  second  place 
the  historical  sciences,  in  the  third  place  the  physical  sciences,  and 
in  the  fourth  place  the  psychical  sciences.  There  cannot  be  a  scientific 
judgment  which  must  not  find  its  place  somewhere  in  one  of  these 
four  groups.  And  yet  can  we  really  say  that  these  four  great  divisions 
complete  the  totality  of  scientific  efforts?  The  plan  of  our  Congress 
contains  three  important  divisions  besides  these. 

5.    The  Three  Divisions  of  Practical  Sciences 

The  three  divisions  which  still  lie"  before  us  represent  Practical 
Knowledge.  Have  we  a  logical  right  to  put  them  on  an  equal  leve.l 
with  the  four  large  divisions  which  we  have  considered  so  far?  Might  it 
not  rather  be  said  that  all  that  is  knowledge  in  those  practical  sciences 
must  find  its  place  somewhere  in  the  theoretical  field,  and  that  every- 
thing outside  of  it  is  not  knowledge,  but  art  ?  It  cannot  be  denied 
indeed  that  the  logical  position  of  the  practical  sciences  presents  seri- 
ous problems.    That  the  function  of  the  engineer  or  of  the  physician, 


THE  THREE  DIVISIONS   OF   PRACTICAL   SCIENCES      117 

of  the  lawyer  or  of  the  minister,  of  the  diplomat  or  of  the  teacher, 
contains  elements  of  an  art  cannot  be  doubted.  They  all  need  not 
only  knowledge,  but  a  certain  instinct  and  power  and  skill,  and  their 
schooling  thus  demands  a  training  and  discipline  through  imitation 
which  cannot  be  substituted  by  mere  learning.  Yet  when  it  comes  to 
the  classification  of  sciences,  it  seems  very  doubtful  whether  practical 
sciences  have  to  be  acknowledged  as  special  divisions,  inasmuch  as 
the  factor  of  art  must  have  been  eliminated  at  the  moment  they  are 
presented  as  sciences.  The  auscultation  of  the  physician  certainly 
demands  skill  and  training,  yet  this  practical  activity  itself  does  not 
enter  into  the  science  of  medicine  as  presented  in  medical  writings. 
As  soon  as  the  physician  begins  to  deal  with  it  scientifically,  he 
needs,  as  does  any  scholar,  not  the  stethoscope,  but  the  pen.  He 
must  formulate  judgments;  and  as  soon  as  he  simply  describes  and 
analyzes  and  explains  and  interprets  his  stethoscopic  experiences, 
his  statements  become  a  system  of  theoretical  ideas. 

We  can  say  in  general  that  the  science  of  medicine  or  of  engineering, 
of  jurisprudence  or  of  education,  contains,  as  science,  no  element  of  art, 
but  merely  theoretical  judgments  which,  as  such,  can  find  their  place 
somewhere  in  the  complete  systems  of  the  theoretical  sciences.  If  the 
physician  describes  a  disease,  its  symptoms,  the  means  of  examining 
them,  the  remedies,  their  therapeutical  effects,  and  the  prophylaxis, 
in  short,  everything  which  the  physician  needs  for  his  art,  he  does  not 
record  anything  which  would  not  belong  to  an  ideally  complete  de- 
scription and  explanation  of  the  processes  in  the  human  body.  In  the 
same  way  it  can  be  said  that  if  the  engineer  characterizes  the  con- 
ditions under  which  an  iron  bridge  will  be  safe,  it  is  evident  that  he 
cannot  introduce  any  facts  which  would  not  find  their  logical  place  in 
an  ideally  complete  description  of  the  properties  of  inorganic  nature; 
and  finally,  the  same  is  true  for  the  statements  of  the  politician,  the 
jurist,  the  pedagogue,  or  the  minister.  Whatever  is  said  about  their 
art  is  a  theoretical  judgment  which  connects  facts  of  the  ideally 
complete  system  of  theoretical  science;  in  their  case  the  facts  of 
course  belong  in  first  line  to  the  realm  of  the  psychological,  his- 
torical, and  normative  sciences.  There  never  has  been  or  can  be 
practical  advice  in  the  form  of  words  which  is  not  in  principle  a  state- 
ment of  facts  which  belong  to  the  absolute  totality  of  theoretical 
knowledge.  Seen  from  this  point  of  view,  it  is  evident  that  all  our 
knowledge  is  fundamentally  theoretical,  and  that  the  conception  of 
practical  knowledge  is  logically  unprecise. 

But  the  opposite  point  of  view  might  also  be  taken.  It  might  be 
said  that  after  all  every  kind  of  knowledge  is  practical,  and  our  own 
deduction  of  the  meaning  of  science  might  be  said  to  suggest  such 
interpretation.  We  acknowledged  at  the  outset  that  the  so-called 
theoretical  knowledge  is  by  no  means  a  passive  mirror-picture  of  an 


118       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

independent  outside  world;  but  that  in  every  judgment  real  expe- 
rience is  remoulded  and  reshaped  in  the  service  of  certain  purposes  of 
will.  Here  lies  the  true  core  of  that  growing  popular  philosophy 
of  to-day  which,  under  the  name  of  pragmatism,  or  under  other  titles, 
mingles  the  purposive  character  of  our  knowledge  and  the  evolution- 
ary theories  of  modern  biology  in  the  vague  notion  that  men  created 
knowledge  because  the  biological  struggle  for  existence  led  to  such 
views  of  the  world;  and  that  we  call  true  that  correlation  of  our 
experiences  which  has  approved  itself  through  its  harmony  with 
the  phylogenetic  development.  Certainly  we  must  reject  such  circle 
philosophies.  We  must  see  clearly  that  the  whole  conception  of  a 
biological  development  and  of  a  struggle  of  organisms  is  itself  only 
a  part  of  our  construction  of  causal  knowledge.  We  must  have  know- 
ledge to  conceive  ourselves  as  products  of  a  phylogenetic  history,  and 
thus  cannot  deduce  from  it  the  fact,  and,  still  less,  the  justification 
of  knowledge.  Yet  one  element  of  this  theory  remains  valuable: 
knowledge  is  indeed  a  purposive  activity,  a  reconstruction  of  the 
world  in  the  service  of  ideals  of  the  will.  We  have  thus  from  one  side 
the  suggestion  that  all  knowledge  is  merely  theoretical,  from  the  other 
side  the  claim  that  all  knowledge  is  practical  activity.  It  seems  as  if 
both  sides  might  agree  that  it  is  superfluous  and  unjustified  to  make 
a  demarcation  line  through  the  field  of  knowledge  and  to  separate 
two  sorts  of  knowledge,  theoretical  and  practical.  For  both  theories 
demand  that  all  knowledge  be  of  one  kind ,  and  they  disagree  only  as 
to  whether  we  ought  to  call  it  all  theoretical  or  all  practical. 

Yet  the  true  situation  is  not  characterized  by  such  an  antithesis. 
If  we  say  that  all  knowledge  is  ultimately  practical,  we  are  speaking 
from  an  epistemological  point  of  view,  inasmuch  as  we  take  it  then  as 
a  reconstruction  of  the  world  through  the  purposive  activity  of  the 
over-individual  subject.  On  the  other  hand  it  is  an  empirical  point  of 
view  from  which  ultimately  all  knowledge,  that  of  the  physician  and 
engineer  and  lawyer,  as  well  as  that  of  the  astronomer,  appears  theo- 
retical. But  this  antithesis  can,  therefore,  not  decide  the  further 
empirical  question,  whether  or  not  in  the  midst  of  theoretical  know- 
ledge two  kinds  of  sciences  may  be  discriminated,  of  which  the  one 
refers  to  empirical  practical  purposes  and  the  other  not.  Such  an 
inquiry  would  have  nothing  to  do  with  the  epistemological  problem  of 
pragmatism ;  it  would  be  strictly  non-philosophical,  just  as  the  separa- 
tion of  chemistry  into  organic  and  inorganic  chemistry.  This  empir- 
ical question  is  indeed  to  be  answered  in  the  affirmative.  If  we  ask 
what  causes  bring  about  a  certain  effect,  for  the  sake  of  a  practical 
purpose  of  ours,  —  for  instance,  the  curing  a  patient  of  a  disease,  —  no 
one  can  state  facts  which  are  not  in  principle  to  be  included  in  the 
complete  system  of  physical  causes  and  effects  and  thus  in  the  system 
of  physical  sciences.  And  yet  it  may  well  be  that  the  physical  sciences, 


THE  THREE  DIVISIONS   OF   PRACTICAL  SCIENCES       119 

as  such,  have  not  the  slightest  reason  to  mention  the  effect  of  that 
special  drug  on  that  special  pathological  alteration  of  the  tissues  of 
the  organism.  The  descriptions  and  explanations  of  science  are  not  a 
mere  heaping  up  of  material,  but  a  steady  selection  in  the  interest  of 
the  special  aim  of  the  science.  No  physical  science  describes  every 
special  pebble  on  the  beach;  no  historical  science  deals  with  the  chance 
happenings  in  the  daily  life  of  any  member  of  the  crowd.  And  we 
already  well  know  the  point  of  view  from  which  the  selection  is  to  be 
performed.  We  want  to  know  in  the  physical  and  psychical  sciences 
whatever  is  involved  in  the  object  of  our  experience,  and  in  the  his- 
torical and  normative  sciences  whatever  is  involved  in  the  demands 
which  reach  our  will.  But  whether  we  have  to  do  with  the  objects  or 
with  the  demands,  in  both  cases  we  have  systems  before  us  which  are 
determined  only  by  the  objects  or  demands  themselves,  without  any 
relation  to  our  individual  will  and  our  own  practical  activity.  Theo- 
retically, of  course,  our  will,  our  activity,  our  organism,  our  person- 
ality is  included  in  the  complete  system;  and  if  we  knew  absolutely 
everything  of  the  empirical  effects  of  the  object  or  of  the  consequences 
of  these  demands,  we  should  find  among  them  their  relation  to  our 
individual  interests;  but  that  relation  would  be  but  one  chance 
case  among  innumerable  others,  and  the  sciences  would  not  have  the 
slightest  interest  in  giving  any  attention  to  that  particular  case.  Thus 
if  our  knowledge  of  chemical  substances  were  complete,  we  should 
certainly  have  to  know  theoretically  that  a  few  grains  of  antipyrine 
introduced  into  the  organism  have  an  influence  on  those  brain  centres 
which  regulate  the  temperature  of  the  human  body.  Yet  if  the  chem- 
ist does  not  share  the  interest  of  the  physician  who  wants  to  fight 
a  fever,  he  would  have  hardly  any  reason  for  examining  this  particular 
relation,  as  it  hardly  throws  light  on  the  chemical  constitution  as 
such.  In  this  way  we  might  say  in  general  that  the  relation  of  the 
world  to  us  as  acting  individuals  is  in  principle  contained  in  the  total 
system  of  the  relations  of  our  world  of  experience,  but  has  a  strictly 
accidental  place  there  and  can  never  be  in  itself  a  centre  around  which 
the  scientific  data  are  clustered,  and  science  will  hardly  have  an  inter- 
est in  giving  any  attention  to  its  details. 

This  relation  of  the  world,  the  phj^sical,  the  psychical,  the  histor- 
ical, and  the  normative  world,  to  our  individual,  practical  purposes 
can,  however,  indeed  become  the  centre  of  scientific  interest,  and  it  is 
evident  that  the  whole  inquiry  receives  thereupon  a  perfectly  new 
direction  which  demands  not  only  a  completely  new  grouping  of  facts 
and  relations,  but  also  "a  very  different  shading  in  elaboration.  As 
long  as  the  purpose  was  to  understand  the  world  without  relation  to 
our  individual  aims,  science  had  to  gather  endless  details  which  are 
for  us  now  quite  indifferent,  as  they  do  not  touch  our  aims;  and  in 
other  respects  science  was  satisfied  with  broad  generalizations  and 


120       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

abstractions  where  we  have  now  to  examine  the  most  minute  details. 
In  short,  the  shifting  of  the  centre  of  gravity  creates  perfectly  new 
sciences  which  must  be  distinguished ;  and  if  we  call  them  again  theo- 
retical and  practical  sciences,  it  is  clear  that  this  difference  has  then 
no  longer  anything  to  do  with  the  philosophical  problems  from  which 
we  started. 

The  term  practical  may  be  preferable  to  the  other  term  which  is 
sometimes  used :  Applied  Science.  If  we  construct  the  antithesis  of 
theoretical  and  applied  science,  the  underlying  idea  is  clearly  that  we 
have  to  do  on  the  practical  side  with  a  discipline  which  teaches  how 
to  apply  a  science  which  logically  exists  as  such  beforehand.  Engin- 
eering, for  instance,  is  an  applied  science  because  it  applies  the 
science  of  physics;  but  this  is  not  reallj^  our  deepest  meaning  here. 
Our  practical  sciences  are  not  meant  as  mere  applications  of  theo- 
retical sciences.  They  are  logically  somewhat  degraded  if  they  are 
treated  in  such  a  way.  Their  real  logical  meaning  comes  out  only  if 
they  are  acknowledged  as  self-dependent  sciences  whose  material  is 
differentiated  from  that  of  the  theoretical  sciences  by  the  different 
point  of  view  and  purpose.  They  are  methodologically  perfectly  inde- 
pendent, and  the  fact  that  a  large  part  or  theoretically  even  every- 
thing of  their  teaching  overlaps  the  teaching  of  certain  theoretical 
sciences  ought  not  to  have  any  influence  on  their  logical  standing. 
The  practical  sciences  could  be  conceived  as  completely  self-depend- 
ent, without  the  existence  of  any  so-called  theoretical  sciences; 
that  is,  the  relations  of  the  world  of  experience  to  our  individual 
aims  might  be  brought  into  complete  systems  without  working  out  in 
principle  the  system  of  independent  experience.  We  might  have  a 
science  of  engineering  without  acknowledging  an  independent  science 
of  theoretical  physics  besides  it.  To  be  sure,  such  a  science  of  engin- 
eering would  finally  develop  itself  into  a  system  which  would  con- 
tain very  much  that  might  just  as  well  be  called  theoretical  physics; 
yet  all  would  be  held  together  by  the  point  of  view  of  the  engineer, 
and  that  part  of  theoretical  physics  which  the  engineer  applies  might 
just  as  well  be  considered  as  depracticalized  engineering.  If  this 
logical  self-dependence  of  the  practical  science  holds  true  even  for 
such  technological  disciplines,  it  is  still  more  evident  that  it  would 
cripple  the  meaning  and  independent  character  of  jurisprudence  and 
social  science,  or  of  pedagogy  and  theology,  to  treat  them  simply  as 
applied  sciences,  that  is,  as  applications  of  theoretical  science. 

This  point  of  view  determines,  also,  of  course,  the  classification  of 
the  Practical  Sciences.  If  they  were  really  merely  applied  sciences 
it  would  be  most  natural  to  group  them  according  to  the  classification 
of  the  theoretical  sciences  which  are  to  be  applied.  We  should  then 
have  applied  physical  sciences,  applied  psychological  sciences,  applied 
historical  sciences,  and  applied  normative  sciences.  Yet  even  from  the 


THE  THREE  DIVISIONS   OF   PRACTICAL  SCIENCES      121 

standpoint  of  practice,  we  should  come  at  once  into  difficulties,  and 
indeed  much  of  the  superficiality  of  practical  sciences  to-day  results 
from  the  hasty  tendency  to  consider  them  as  applied  sciences  only, 
and  thus  to  be  determined  by  the  points  of  view  of  the  theoretical  dis- 
cipline which  is  to  be  applied.  Then,  for  instance,  pedagogy  becomes 
simply  applied  psychology,  and  the  psychological  point  of  view  is 
substituted  for  the  educational  one.  Pedagogy  then  becomes  simply 
a  selection  of  those  chapters  in  psychology  which  deal  with  the  mental 
functions  of  the  child.  Yet  as  soon  as  we  really  take  the  teachers' 
point  of  view,  we  understand  at  once  that  it  is  utterly  artificial  to  sub- 
stitute the  categories  of  the  psychologist  for  those  of  immediate 
practical  will-relations  and  to  consider  the  child  in  the  class-room  as 
a  causal  system  of  pyscho-physical  elements  instead  of  a  personality 
which  is  teleologically  to  be  interpreted,  and  whose  aims  are  not  to  be 
connected  with  causal  effects  but  with  over-individual  attitudes.  In 
this  way  the  historical  relation  and  the  normative  relation  have  to 
play  at  least  as  important  a  role  in  the  pedagogical  system  as  the 
psycho-physical  relation,  and  we  might  quite  as  well  call  education 
applied  history  and  applied  ethics. 

Almost  every  practical  science  can  be  shown  in  this  way  to  apply 
a  number  of  theoretical  sciences;  it  synthesizes  them  to  a  new  unity. 
But  better,  we  ought  to  say,  that  it  is  a  unity  in  itself  from  the  start, 
and  that  it  only  overlaps  with  a  number  of  theoretical  sciences.  If 
we  want  to  classify  the  practical  sciences,  we  have  thus  only  the  one 
logical  principle  at  our  disposal :  we  must  classify  them  in  accordance 
with  the  group  of  human  individual  aims  which  control  those  dif- 
ferent disciplines.  If  all  practical  sciences  deal  with  the  relation  of 
the  world  of  experience  to  our  individual  practical  ends,  the  classes  of 
those  ends  are  the  classes  of  our  practical  sciences,  whatever  combina- 
tions of  applied  theoretical  sciences  may  enter  into  the  group.  Of 
course  a  special  classification  of  these  aims  must  remain  somewhat 
arbitrary ;  yet  it  may  seem  most  natural  to  separate  three  large  divi- 
sions. We  called  them  the  Utilitarian  Sciences,  the  Sciences  of  Social 
Regulation,  and  the  Sciences  of  Social  Culture.  Utilitarian  we  may 
call  those  sciences  in  which  our  practical  aim  refers  to  the  world  of 
things;  it  maybe  the  technical  mastery  of  nature  or  the  treatment 
of  the  body,  or  the  production,  distribution,  and  consumption  of  the 
means  of  support.  The  second  division  contains  everything  in  which 
our  aim  does  not  refer  to  the  thing,  but  to  the  other  subjects;  here 
naturally  belong  the  sciences  which  deal  with  the  political,  legal,  and 
social  purposes.  And  finally  the  sciences  of  culture  refer  to  those  aims 
in  which  not  the  individual  relations  to  things  or  to  other  subjects  are 
in  the  foreground,  but  the  purposes  of  the  teleological  development  of 
the  subject  himself;  education,  art,  and  religion  here  find  their  place. 
It  is,  of  course,  evident  that  the  material  of  these  sciences  frequently 


122       THE   SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF   THE  CONGRESS 

allows  the  emphasis  of  different  aspects.  For  instance,  education, 
which  aims  primarily  at  self-development,  might  quite  well  be  con- 
sidered also  from  the  point  of  view  of  social  regulation;  and  still 
more  naturally  could  the  utilitarian  sciences  of  the  economic  distri- 
bution of  the  means  of  support  be  considered  from  this  point  of 
view.  Yet  a  classification  of  sciences  nowhere  suggests  by  its 
boundary  lines  that  there  are  no  relations  and  connections  between 
the  different  parts;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  just  the  manifoldness  of 
these  given  connections  which  makes  it  so  desirable  to  become  con- 
scious of  the  principles  involved,  and  thus  to  emphasize  logical 
demarcation  lines,  which  of  course  must  be  obliterated  as  soon  as 
any  material  is  to  be  treated  from  every  possible  point  of  view.  It  may 
thus  well  be  that,  for  instance,  a  certain  industrial  problem  could  be 
treated  in  the  Normative  Sciences  from  the  point  of  view  of  ethics;  in 
the  Historical  Sciences,  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  history  of 
economic  institutions;  in  the  Physical  Sciences,  from  the  point  of 
view  of  physics  or  chemistry;  in  the  Mental  Sciences,  from  the  point 
of  view  of  sociology;  in  the  Utilitarian  Sciences,  from  the  point  of 
view  of  medicine  or  of  engineering,  or  of  commerce  and  transporta- 
tion; and  finally  in  the  Regulative  Sciences,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
political  administration,  or  in  the  Social  Sciences,  from  the  standpoint 
of  the  urban  community,  and  so  on.  The  more  complex  the  relations 
are,  the  more  necessary  is  it  to  make  clean  distinctions  between  the 
different  logical  purposes  with  which  the  scientific  inquiries  start. 
Practical  life  may  demand  a  combination  of  historical,  sociological, 
psychological,  economical,  social,  and  ethical  considerations;  but  not 
one  of  these  sciences  can  contribute  its  best  if  the  consciousness  of 
these  differences  is  lost  and  the  deliberate  combination  is  replaced  by 
a  vague  mixture  of  the  problems. 

6.   The  Subdivisions 

We  have  now  before  us  the  ground-plan  of  the  scheme,  the  four 
theoretical  divisions,  and  the  three  practical  divisions;  every  addi- 
tional comment  on  the  classification  must  be  of  secondary  importance, 
as  it  has  to  refer  to  the  smaller  subdivisions,  which  cannot  change  the 
principles  of  the  plan,  and  which  have  not  seldom,  indeed,  been  a  re- 
sult of  practical  considerations.  If,  for  instance,  our  Division  of  Cul- 
tural Sciences  shows  in  the  final  plan  merely  the  departments  of 
Education  and  of  Religion,  while  the  originally  planned  Department 
of  Art  is  left  out,  there  was  no  logical  reason  for  it,  but  merely  the 
practical  ground  that  it  seemed  difficult  to  bring  such  a  practical  art 
section  to  a  desirable  scientific  level;  we  confine  art,  therefore,  to 
the  normative  aesthetic  and  historical  points  of  view.  Or,  to  choose 
another  illustration,  if  it  happened  that  the  normative  sciences  were 


THE  SUBDIVISIONS  123 

finally  organized  without  a  section  for  the  philosophy  of  law,  this  re- 
sulted from  the  fact  that  the  American  jurists,  in  contrast  with  their 
Continental  European  colleagues,  showed  a  general  lack  of  appre- 
ciation for  such  a  section.  A  few  sections  had  to  be  left  out  even  for 
the  chance  reason  that  the  leading  speakers  were  obliged  to  with- 
draw at  a  time  when  it  was  too  late  to  ask  substitutes  to  work  up 
addresses.  And  almost  everywhere  there  had  to  be  something  arbi- 
trary in  the  limitation  of  the  special  sections.  Though  Otology  and 
Laryngology  were  brought  together  into  one  section,  they  might  just 
as  well  have  been  placed  in  two ;  and  Rhinology ,  which  was  left  out, 
might  have  been  added  as  a  third  in  that  company.  As  to  this  sub- 
tler ramification,  the  plan  has  been  changed  several  times  during  the 
period  of  the  practical  preparation  of  the  plan,  and  much  is  the  result 
of  adjustment  to  questions  of  personalities.  No  one  claims,  thus, 
any  special  logical  value  for  the  final  formulation  of  the  sectional 
details,  for  which  our  chief  aim  was  not  to  go  beyond  eight  times 
sixteen,  that  is  128,  sections,  inasmuch  as  it  was  planned  to  have 
the  meetings  at  eight  different  time-periods  in  sixteen  different  halls. 
If  we  had  fulfilled  all  the  wishes  which  were  expressed  by  specialists, 
the  number  would  have  been  quickly  doubled. 

Yet  a  few  remarks  may  be  devoted  to  the  branching  off  within  the 
seven  divisions,  as  a  short  discussion  of  some  of  these  details  may 
throw  additional  light  on  the  general  principles  of  the  whole  plan.  If 
we  thus  begin  with  the  Normative  Sciences,  we  stand  at  once  before 
one  feature  of  the  plan  which  has  been  in  an  especially  high  degree 
a  matter  of  both  approval  and  criticism :  the  fact  that  Mathematics 
is  grouped  with  Philosophy.  The  Division  was  to  contain,  as  we  have 
seen,  the  systems  of  logically  connected  wiU-acts  of  the  over-individ- 
ual subject.  That  Ethics  or  Logic  or  ^Esthetics  or  Philosophy  of 
Religion  deals  with  such  over-individual  attitudes  cannot  be  doubted; 
but  have  we  a  right  to  coordinate  the  mathematical  sciences  with 
these  philosophical  sciences?  Has  Mathematics  not  a  more  natural 
place  among  the  physical  sciences  coordinated  with  and  introductory 
to  Mechanics,  Physics,  and  Astronomy?  The  mathematicians  them- 
selves would  often  be  inclined  to  accept  without  hesitation  this  neigh- 
borhood of  the  physical  sciences.  They  would  say  that  the  mathe- 
matical objects  are  independent  realities  whose  properties  we  study 
like  those  of  nature,  whose  relations  we  "observe,"  whose  existence 
we  "discover,"  and  in  which  we  are  interested  because  they  belong  to 
the  real  world.  All  this  is  true,  and  yet  the  objects  of  the  mathema- 
tician are  objects  made  by  the  logical  will  only,  and  thus  different 
from  all  phenomena  into  which  sensation  enters.  The  mathema- 
tician, of  course,  does  not  reflect  on  the  purely  logical  origin  of  the 
objects  which  he  studies,  but  the  system  of  knowledge  must  give  to 
the  study  of  the  mathematical  objects  its  place  in  the  group  where  the 


124       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF   THE  CONGRESS 

functions  and  products  of  the  over-individual  attitudes  are  classified. 
The  mathematical  object  is  a  free  creation,  and  a  creation  not  only 
as  to  the  combination  of  elements  —  that  would  be  the  case  with 
many  laboratory  substances  of  the  chemist  too  —  but  a  creation  as  to 
the  elements  themselves,  and  the  value  of  that  creation,  its  "  mathe- 
matical interest,"  is  to  be  judged  by  ideals  of  thought;  that  is,  by 
logical  purposes.  No  doubt  this  logical  purpose  is  its  application  in 
the  world  of  objects  and  the  mathematical  concepts  must  thus  fit  the 
objective  world  so  absolutely  that  mathematics  can  be  conceived  as  a 
description  of  the  world  after  abstracting  not  only  from  the  will-rela- 
tions, as  physics  does,  but  also  from  the  content.  Mathematics  would, 
then,  be  the  phenomenalistic  science  of  the  form  and  order  of  the 
world.  In  this  way,  mathematics  has  indeed  a  claim  to  places  in  both 
divisions:  among  the  physical  sciences  if  we  emphasize  its  applica- 
bility to  the  world,  and  among  the  teleological  sciences  if  we  empha- 
size the  free  creation  of  the  objects  by  the  logical  will.  But  if  we  really 
go  back  to  epistemological  principles,  our  system  has  to  prefer  the 
latter  emphasis;  that  is,  we  must  coordinate  mathematics  with  logic 
and  not  with  physics. 

As  to  the  subdivision  of  philosophy,  it  is  most  essential  for  us  to 
point  to  the  negative  fact  that  of  course  psychology  cannot  have  a 
place  in  the  philosophical  department,  as  part  of  the  Normative  Divi- 
sion. There  is  perhaps  no  science  whose  position  in  the  system  of 
knowledge  offers  so  many  methodological  difficulties  as  psychology. 
Historical  tradition  of  course  links  it  with  philosophy;  throughout  a 
great  part  of  its  present  endeavors  it  is,  on  the  other  hand,  linked  with 
physiology.  Thus  we  find  it  sometimes  coordinated  with  logic  and 
ethics,  and  sometimes,  especially  in  the  classical  positivistic  systems, 
coordinated  with  the  sciences  of  the  organic  functions.  We  have  seen 
why  a  really  logical  treatment  has  to  disregard  those  historical  and 
practical  relations  and  has  to  separate  the  psychological  sciences  from 
the  philosophical  and  the  biological  sciences.  Yet  even  this  does 
not  complete  the  list  of  problems  which  must  be  settled,  inasmuch 
as  modern  thinkers  have  frequently  insisted  that  psychology  itself 
allows  a  twofold  aspect.  We  can  have  a  psychology  which  describes 
and  explains  the  mental  life  by  analyzing  it  into  its  elements  and  by 
connecting  these  elements  through  causality.  But  there  may  be 
another  psychology  which  treats  inner  life  in  that  immediate  unity  in 
which  we  experience  it  and  seeks  to  interpret  it  as  the  free  function 
of  personality.  This  latter  kind  of  psychology  has  been  called  volun- 
taristic  psychology  as  against  the  phenomenalistic  psychology  which 
seeks  description  and  explanation.  Such  voluntaristic  psychology 
would  clearly  belong  again  to  a  different  division.  It  would  be  a 
theory  of  individual  life  as  a  function  of  will,  and  would  thus  be 
introductory  to  the  historical  sciences  and  to  the  normative  sciences 


THE  SUBDIVISIONS  125 

too.  Yet  we  left  out  this  teleological  psychology  from  our  programme, 
as  such  a  science  is  as  yet  a  programme  only.  Wherever  an  effort  is 
made  to  realize  it,  it  becomes  an  odd  mixture  of  an  inconsistent  phe- 
nomenalistic  psychology  on  the  one  side,  and  philosophy  of  history, 
logic,  ethics,  and  aesthetics  on  the  other  side.  The  only  science  which 
really  has  a  right  to  call  itself  psychology  is  the  one  which  seeks  to 
describe  and  to  explain  inner  life  and  treats  it  therefore  as  a  system 
of  psychical  objects,  that  is,  as  contents  of  consciousness,  that  is,  as 
phenomena.  Psychology  belongs,  then,  in  the  general  division  of 
psychical  sciences  as  over  against  physical  sciences,  and  both  deal 
with  objects  as  over  against  philosophy  and  history,  which  deal  with 
subjects  of  will. 

The  subdivision  of  the  Historical  Sciences  offers  no  methodological 
difficulty  as  soon  as  those  epistemological  arguments  are  acknow- 
ledged by  which  we  sharply  distinguish  history  from  the  Physical 
and  Mental  Sciences.  If  history  is  a  system  of  will-relations  which 
is  in  teleological  connection  with  the  will-demands  that  surround  us, 
then  political  history  loses  its  predominant  role,  and  the  history  of 
law  and  of  literature,  of  language  and  of  economy,  of  art  and  relig- 
ion, become  coordinated  with  political  development,  while  the  mere 
anthropological  aspect  of  man  is  relegated  to  the  physical  sciences. 
The  more  complete  original  scheme  was  here  again  finally  condensed 
for  practical  reasons;  for  instance,  the  planned  departments  on  the 
History  of  Education,  on  the  History  of  Science,  and  on  the  History 
of  Philosophy  were  sacrificed,  and  the  department  of  Economic  His- 
tory was  joined  to  that  of  Political  History.  In  the  same  way  we  felt 
obliged  to  omit  in  the  end  many  important  sections  in  the  depart- 
ments; we  had,  for  instance,  in  the  History  of  Language  at  first  a  sec- 
tion on  Slavic  Languages ;  yet  the  number  of  scholars  interested  was 
too  small  to  justify  its  existence  beside  a  section  on  Slavic  Literature. 
Also  the  History  of  Music  was  omitted  from  the  History  of  Art;  and 
the  History  of  Law  was  planned  at  first  with  a  fuller  ramification. 

The  division  of  Physical  Sciences  naturally  suggested  that  kind  of 
subdivision  which  the  positivistic  classification  presents  as  a  com- 
plete system  of  sciences.  Considering  physics  and  chemistry  as  the 
two  fundamental  sciences  of  general  laws,  we  turn  first  to  astronomy, 
then  from  the  science  of  the  whole  universe  to  the  one  planet,  to  the 
sciences  of  the  earth;  thence  to  the  living  organisms  on  the  earth;  and 
from  biology  to  the  still  narrower  circle  of  anthropology.  The  special 
classification  of  physics  offers  a  certain  difficulty.  To  divide  it  in  text- 
book fashion  into  sound,  light,  electricity,  etc.,  seems  hardly  in  har- 
mony with  the  effort  to  seek  logical  principles  in  the  other  parts  of  the 
classification.  The  three  groups  which  we  finally  formed,  Physics  of 
Matter,  Physics  of  Ether,  and  Physics  of  Electron,  may  appear  some- 
what too  much  influenced  by  the  latest  theories  of  to-day,  yet  it 


126       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF   THE  CONGRESS 

seemed  preferable  to  other  principles.  In  the  biological  department, 
criticism  seems  justified  in  view  of  the  fact  that  we  constructed 
a  special  section,  Human  Anatomy.  A  strictly  logical  scheme  might 
have  acknowledged  that  human  anatomy  is  to-day  not  a  separate 
science,  and  that  it  has  resolved  itself  into  comparative  anatomy. 
Sections  of  Invertebrate  and  Vertebrate  Anatomy  might  have  been 
more  satisfactory.  The  final  arrangement  was  a  concession  to  the 
practical  interests  of  the  physicians,  who  have  naturally  to  emphasize 
the  anatomy  of  the  human  organism. 

In  the  division  of  Mental  Sciences,  we  have  the  Department  of 
Sociology.  We  were,  of  course,  aware  that  the  sociological  interest 
includes  not  only  the  psychological,  but  also  the  physiological  life 
of  society,  and  that  it  thus  has  relations  to  the  physical  sciences 
too.  Yet  these  relations  are  logically  not  more  fundamental  than 
those  of  the  individual  mental  life  to  the  functions  of  the  indi- 
vidual organism.  Much  of  the  physiological  side  was  further  to 
be  handed  over  to  the  Department  of  Anthropology,  and  thus  we 
felt  justified  in  grouping  sociology  with  psychology  under  the  Men- 
tal Sciences,  as  the  psychology  of  the  social  organism.  Here,  too, 
a  larger  number  of  sections  was  intended  and  only  the  two  most 
essential  ones,  Social  Structure  and  Social  Psychology,  were  finally 
admitted. 

The  ramifications  of  the  practical  sciences  had  to  follow  the  general 
principle  that  their  character  is  determined  by  purpose  and  not  by 
material.  The  difficulty  was  here  merely  in  the  extreme  specialization 
of  the  practical  disciplines,  which  suggests  on  the  whole  the  forming  of 
very  small  units,  while  our  plan  was  to  provide  for  fifty  practical  sec- 
tions only.  It  seemed,  therefore,  incongruous  to  have  the  whole  of 
Internal  Medicine  or  the  whole  of  Private  Law  condensed  into  one 
section.  Yet  as  the  purpose  of  the  scheme  was  a  theoretical  and  not  a 
practical  one,  even  where  the  theory  of  practical  sciences  was  in  ques- 
tion, we  felt  justified  in  constructing  coordinated  sections,  even  where 
the  practical  importance  was  very  unequal.  On  the  other  hand,  some 
glaring  defects  just  here  are  due  merely  to  chance  circumstances. 
That  there  were,  for  instance,  no  sections  on  Criminal  Law  or  Eccle- 
siastical Law  in  the  Department  of  Jurisprudence,  nor  on  Legal  Pro- 
cedure, resulted  from  the  unfortunate  accident  that  in  these  cases  the 
speakers  who  were  to  come  from  Europe  were  withheld  by  illness  or 
public  duties.  The  absence  of  the  Department  of  Art  in  the  Division 
of  Social  Culture,  and  thus  of  the  Sections  on  the  theory  and  practice 
of  the  different  arts,  has  been  explained  before.  It  is  evident  that 
also  in  the  Economical  Department  the  practical  development  has 
interfered  with  the  original  symmetrical  arrangement  of  the  sec- 
tions. This  is  not  true  of  the  Religious  Department,  whose  six 
sections  express    the  tendencies  of    the  original  plan.     The   fre- 


THE  RESULTS   OF   THE   CONGRESS  127 

quently  expressed  criticism  that  the  different  rehgions  and  their 
denominations  ought  to  have  found  place  there  shows  a  mis- 
conception of  our  purpose;  a  Parliament  of  Religion  did  not  belong 
to  this  plan. 

Ill 

THE   RESULTS   OF   THE   CONGRESS 

The  programme  of  the  Congress,  as  outlined  in  the  previous 
pages,  was  in  this  case  somewhat  more  than  a  mere  programme.  It 
not  onl}^  invited  to  do  a  piece  of  work,  but  it  sought  to  contribute  to 
the  work  itself.  Yet  the  chief  work  had  to  be  done  by  others,  and 
their  part  needed  careful  preparation.  Yet  very  little  of  the  prepar- 
ation showed  itself  to  the  eyes  of  the  larger  public,  and  few  were  fully 
aware  what  a  complex  organization  was  growing  up  and  how  many 
persons  of  mark  were  cooperating. 

It  was  essential  to  find  for  every  address  the  best  man.  Specialists 
only  could  suggest  to  the  committees  where  to  find  him.  It  has  been 
told  before  how  our  invitations  were  brought  to  the  foreigners  first 
till  the  desired  number  of  foreign  participants  was  secured,  and  how 
the  Americans  followed.  As  could  not  be  otherwise  expected,  interfer- 
ences of  all  kinds  disturbed  the  ideal  configuration  of  the  first  list  of 
acceptances;  substitutes  had  sometimes  to  be  relied  on;  and  yet, 
when  on  the  nineteenth  of  September  President  Francis  welcomed  the 
Congress  of  Arts  and  Science  in  the  gigantic  Festival  Hall  of  the  St. 
Louis  Exposition,  the  Committee  knew  that  almost  four  hundred 
speakers  had  completed  their  manuscripts,  and  that  it  was  a  galaxy 
which  far  surpassed  in  importance  that  of  any  previous  international 
congress.  And  the  list  of  those  who  stood  for  the  success  of  the  work 
was  not  confined  to  the  official  speakers.  Each  Department  and  each 
Section  had  its  own  honorary  President,  who  was  also  chosen  by  the 
consent  of  leading  specialists  and  whose  introductory  remarks  were  to 
give  additional  importance  to  the  gathering.  At  their  side  stood  the 
hundred  and  thirty  Secretaries,  carefully  chosen  from  among  the  pro- 
ductive scholars  of  the  younger  generation.  And  a  large  number  of 
informal,  yet  officially  invited  contributors,  had  announced  valuable 
discussions  and  addresses  for  almost  every  Section.  Invitations  to 
membership  finally  had  been  sent  to  the  universities  and  scholarly 
societies  of  all  countries. 

That  the  turmoil  of  a  world's  fair  is  out  of  harmony  with  the 
scholar's  longing  for  repose  and  quietude  is  a  natural  presupposition, 
which  has  not  been  disproved  by  the  experience  of  St.  Louis.  When 
Professor  Newcomb,  our  President,  spoke  to  the  opening  assembly  on 
the  dignity  of  scholarship,  the  scholar's  peaceful  address  was  accentu- 


128       THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF   THE   CONGRESS 

ated  by  the  thunder  of  the  cannons  with  which  Boer  and  British 
forces  were  playing  at  war  near  by.  The  roaring  of  the  Pike  over- 
powered many  a  quiet  session,  and  the  patient  speaker  had  not  seldom 
to  fight  heroically  with  a  brass  band  on  the  next  lawn.  The  trains 
were  delayed,  trunks  were  mixed  up,  and  the  sultry  St.  Louis  weather 
stirred  much  secret  longing  for  the  seashore  and  the  mountains,  which 
most  had  to  leave  too  early  for  that  pilgrimage  to  the  Mississippi 
Valley.  Yet  all  this  could  have  been  easily  foreseen,  and  every  one 
knew  that  all  this  would  soon  be  forgotten.  These  slight  discomforts 
were  many  times  made  up  for  by  the  overwhelming  beauty  of  that 
ivory  city  in  which  the  civilization  of  the  world  was  focused  by  the 
united  energy  of  the  nations,  and  it  seemed  well  worth  while  to  cross 
the  ocean  for  the  delight  of  that  enchantment  which  came  with  every 
evening's  myriad  illumination.  And  every  day  brought  interesting 
festivities.  No  one  will  forget  the  receptions  of  the  foreign  commis- 
sioners, or  the  charming  hospitality  of  the  leading  citizens  of  St.  Louis, 
or  the  enthusiastic  banquet  which  brought  one  thousand  speakers 
and  presidents  and  official  members  of  the  Congress  together  as  guests 
of  the  master  mind  of  the  Exposition,  President  Francis. 

While  the  discomfort  of  external  shortcomings  was  thus  easily  bal- 
anced, it  is  more  doubtful  whether  the  internal  shortcomings  of  the 
work  can  be  considered  as  fully  compensated  for.  It  would  be  impos- 
sible to  overlook  these  defects  in  the  realization  of  our  plans,  even  if  it 
may  be  acknowledged  that  they  were  unavoidable  under  the  given 
conditions.  The  principal  difficulty  has  been  that  many  speakers 
have  not  really  treated  the  topic  for  the  discussion  of  which  they  were 
invited.  This  deviation  from  the  plan  took  various  forms.  There  was 
in  some  cases  a  fundamental  attitude  taken  which  did  not  harmonize 
with  those  logical  principles  which  had  led  to  the  classification;  for 
instance,  we  had  sharply  separated,  for  reasons  fully  stated  above, 
the  Division  of  History  from  the  Division  of  Mental  Sciences,  includ- 
ing sociology;  yet  some  papers  for  the  Division  of  History  clearly 
indicated  sympathy  with  the  traditional  positivistic  view,  according 
to  which  history  becomes  simply  a  part  of  sociology.  And  sunilar 
variations  of  the  general  plan  occur  in  almost  every  division.  But 
there  cannot  be  any  objection  to  this  secondary  variety  as  long  as  the 
whole  framework  gives  the  primary  uniformity.  Certainly  no  ore  of 
the  contributors  is  to  be  blamed  for  it;  no  one  was  pledged  to  the 
philosophy  of  the  general  plan,  and  probably  few  would  have  agreed 
if  any  one  had  had  the  idea  of  demanding  from  every  contributor  an 
identical  background  of  general  convictions.  Such  monotony  would 
have  been  even  harmful,  as  the  work  would  have  become  inexpressive 
of  the  richness  of  tendencies  in  the  scholarly  life  of  our  time.  This  was 
not  an  occasion  where  educated  clerks  were  to  work  up  in  a  second- 
hand way  a  report  whose  general  trend  was  determined  beforehand; 


THE  RESULTS   OF   THE   CONGRESS  129 

the  work  demanded  original  thinkers,  with  whom  every  word  grows 
out  of  a  rich  individual  view  of  the  totality.  If  every  paper  had  been 
meant  merely  as  a  detailed  amplification  of  the  logical  principles 
on  which  the  whole  plan  was  based,  it  would  have  been  wiser  to  set 
young  Doctor  candidates  to  work,  who  might  have  elaborated  the 
hint  of  the  general  scheme.  To  invite  the  leaders  of  knowledge  meant 
to  give  them  complete  freedom  and  to  confine  the  demands  of  the  plan 
to  a  most  general  direction. 

The  same  freedom,  which  every  one  was  to  have  as  to  the  general 
standpoint,  was  intended  also  for  all  with  regard  to  the  arrangement 
and  limitation  of  the  topic.  All  the  sectional  addresses  were  supposed 
to  deal  either  with  relations  or  with  fundamental  problems  of  to-day. 
It  would  have  been  absurd  to  demand  that  in  every  case  the  totality 
of  relations  or  of  problems  should  be  covered  or  even  touched.  The 
result  would  have  become  perfunctory  and  insignificant.  No  one 
intended  to  produce  a  cyclopedia.  It  was  essential  everywhere  to 
select  that  which  was  most  characteristic  of  the  tendencies  of  the  age 
and  most  promising  for  the  science  of  the  twentieth  century.  Those 
problems  were  to  be  emphasized  whose  solution  is  most  demanded  for 
the  immediate  progress  of  knowledge,  and  those  relations  had  to  be 
selected  through  which  new  connections,  new  synthetic  thoughts 
prepare  themselves  to-day.  That  this  selection  had  to  be  left  to  the 
speaker  was  a  matter  of  course. 

Yet  it  may  be  said  that  in  all  these  directions,  with  reference  to  the 
general  standpoint  and  with  reference  to  problems  and  relations, 
the  Organizing  Committee  had  somewhat  prepared  the  choice  through 
the  selection  of  the  speakers  themselves.  As  the  standpoints  of  the 
leading  speakers  were  well  known,  it  was  not  difficult  to  invite  as  far 
as  possible  for  every  place  a  scholar  whose  general  views  would  be 
least  out  of  harmony  with  the  principles  of  the  plan.  For  instance, 
when  we  had  the  task  before  us  of  selecting  the  divisional  speakers  for 
the  Normative  and  for  the  Mental  Sciences,  it  was  only  natural  to 
invite  for  the  first  a  philosopher  of  idealistic  type  and  for  the  latter  a 
philosopher  of  positivistic  stamp,  inasmuch  as  the  whole  scheme  gave 
to  the  mental  sciences  the  same  place  which  they  would  have  had  in 
a  positivistic  scheme,  while  the  normative  sciences  would  have  lost 
the  meaning  which  they  had  in  our  plan  if  a  positivist  had  simply 
psychologized  them.  In  the  same  way  we  gave  preference  as  far  as 
possible,  for  the  addresses  on  relations,  to  those  scholars  whose  pre- 
vious work  was  concerned  with  new  synthetic  movements,  and  as 
speakers  on  problem^  those  were  invited  who  were  in  any  case 
engaged  in  the  solution  of  those  problems  which  seemed  central  in 
the  present  state  of  science.  Thus  it  was  that  on  the  whole  the  ex- 
pectation was  justified  that  the  most  characteristic  relations  and  the 
most  characteristic  problems  would  be  selected  if  every  imdted 


130       THE  SCIENTIFIC   PLAN   OF  THE  CONGRESS 

speaker  spoke  essentially  on  those  relations  and  on  those  problems 
with  which  his  own  special  work  was  engaged. 

Yet  there  is  no  doubt  that  this  expectation  was  sometimes  ful- 
filled beyond  our  anticipation,  in  an  amount  of  specialization  which 
was  no  longer  entirely  in  harmony  with  the  general  character  of  the 
undertaking.  The  general  problem  has  become  sometimes  only  the 
starting-point  or  almost  the  pretext  for  speaking  on  some  relation 
or  problem  &o  detailed  that  it  can  hardly  stand  as  a  representative 
symbol  of  the  whole  movement  in  that  sectional  field.  Especially  in 
the  practical  sciences  more  room  was  sometimes  taken  for  particu- 
lar hobbies  and  chance  aspects  than  in  the  eyes  of  the  originators  the 
occasion  may  have  called  for.  Yet  on  the  whole  this  was  the  excep- 
tion. The  overwhelming  majority  of  the  addresses  fulfilled  nobly  the 
high  hopes  of  the  Boards,  and  even  in  those  exceptional  cases  where 
the  speaker  went  his  own  way,  it  was  usually  such  an  original  and 
stimulating  expression  of  a  strong  personality  that  no  one  would  care 
to  miss  this  tone  in  the  symphony  of  science. 

Even  now  of  course,  though  the  Congress  days  have  passed,  and 
only  typewritten  manuscripts  are  left  from  all  those  September 
meetings,  it  would  be  easy  to  provide,  by  editorial  efforts,  for  a  greater 
uniformity  and  a  smoother  harmonization.  Most  of  the  authors 
would  have  been  quite  willing  to  retouch  their  addresses  in  the 
interest  of  greater  objective  uniformity  and  to  accept  the  hint  of  an 
editorial  committee  in  elaborating  more  fully  some  points  and  in  con- 
densing or  eliminating  others.  Much  was  written  in  the  desire  to  bring 
a  certain  thought  for  discussion  before  such  an  eminent  audience, 
while  the  speaker  would  be  ready  to  substitute  other  features  of  the 
subject  for  the  permanent  form  of  the  printed  volume.  Yet  such 
editorial  supervision  and  transformation  would  be  not  only  immodest 
but  dangerous.  We  might  risk  gaining  some  external  uniformity,  but 
only  to  lose  much  of  the  freshness  and  immediacy  and  brilliancy  of 
the  first  presentation.  And  who  would  dare  to  play  the  critical  judge 
when  the  international  contributors  are  the  leaders  of  thought  ? 
There  was  therefore  not  the  slightest  effort  made  to  suggest  revision 
of  the  manuscripts,  for  which  the  whole  responsibility  must  thus  fall 
to  the  particular  author.  The  reduction  to  a  uniform  language 
seemed,  on  the  other  hand,  most  natural,  and  those  who  had  delivered 
their  addresses  in  French,  German,  or  Italian  themselves  welcomed 
the  idea  that  their  papers  should  be  translated  into  English  by  com- 
petent specialists.  The  short  bibliographies,  selected  mostly  through 
the  chairman  of  the  departments,  and  the  very  full  index  with  refer- 
ences may  add  to  the  general  usefulness  of  the  eight  volumes  in  which 
the  work  is  to  be  presented. 

But  the  significance  of  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science  ought  not 
to  be  measured  and  valued  only  by  reference  to  this  printed  result. 


THE  RESULTS  OF  THE  CONGRESS  131 

Its  less  visible  side-effects  seem  in  no  way  less  important  for  scholar- 
ship, and  they  are  fourfold.  There  was,  first,  the  personal  contact 
between  the  scholarly  public  and  the  leaders  of  thought;  there  was, 
secondly,  the  first  academic  alliance  between  the  United  States  and 
Europe;  there  was,  thirdly,  the  first  demonstration  of  a  world  con- 
gress crystallized  about  one  problem;  there  was,  fourthly,  the  unique 
accentuation  of  the  thought  of  unity  in  all  human  science;  and  each 
of  these  four  movements  will  be  continued  and  reinforced  by  the  pub- 
lication of  these  proceedings. 

The  first  of  these  four  features,  the  contact  of  the  scholarly  public 
with  the  best  thinkers  of  our  time,  had,  to  be  sure,  its  limitations.  It 
was  not  sought  to  create  a  really  popular  congress.  Neither  the  level 
of  the  addresses,  nor  the  size  of  the  halls,  nor  the  number  of  invita- 
tions sent  out,  nor  the  general  conditions  of  a  world's  fair  at  which 
the  expense  of  living  is  high  and  the  distractions  thousandfold, 
favored  the  attendance  of  crowds.  It  was  planned  from  the  first  that 
on  the  whole  scholars  and  specialists  should  attend  and  that  the  army 
should  be  made  up  essentially  of  officers.  If  in  an  astronomical  section 
perhaps  thirty  men  were  present,  among  whom  practically  every  one 
was  among  the  best  known  directors  of  observatories  or  professors  of 
mathematics,  astronomy,  or  physics,  from  all  countries  of  the  globe, 
much  more  was  gained  than  if  three  thousand  had  been  in  the  audi- 
ence, brought  together  by  an  interest  of  curiosity  in  moon  and  stars. 
For  the  most  part  there  must  have  been  between  a  hundred  and  two 
hundred  in  each  of  the  128  sectional  meetings,  and  that  was  more 
than  the  organizers  expected.  This  direct  influence  on  the  inter- 
ested public  is  now  to  be  expanded  a  thousandfold  by  the  mission 
work  of  these  volumes.  The  concentration  of  these  hundreds  of 
addresses  into  a  few  days  made  it  in  any  case  impossible  to  listen  to 
more  than  to  a  small  fraction;  these  volumes  will  bring  at  last  all 
speakers  to  coordinated  effectiveness;  and  while  one  hall  suffered 
from  bad  acoustics,  another  from  bad  ventilation,  and  a  third  from 
the  passing  of  the  intermural  trains,  here  at  least  is  an  audience  in 
which  nothing  will  disturb  the  sensitive  nerves  of  the  willing  follower. 

But  much  more  emphasis  is  due  to  the  second  feature.  The  Con- 
gress was  an  epoch-making  event  for  the  international  world  of 
scholarship  from  the  fact  that  it  was  the  first  great  undertaking  in 
which  the  Old  and  the  New  Worlds  stood  on  equal  levels  and  in  which 
Europe  really  became  acquainted  with  the  scientific  life  of  these 
United  States.  The  contact  of  scholarship  between  America  and  Eu- 
rope has,  indeed,  grown  in  importance  through  many  decades.  Many 
American  students  had  studied  in  European  and  especially  in  German 
universities  and  had  come  back  to  fill  the  professorial  chairs  of  the 
leading  academic  institutions.  The  spirit  of  the  Graduate  School  and 
the  work  towards  the  Doctor's  degree,  yes,  the  whole  productive 


132       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

scholarship  of  recent  decades  had  been  influenced  by  European  ideals, 
and  the  results  were  no  longer  ignored  at  the  seats  of  learning  through- 
out the  whole  world.  European  scholars  had  here  and  there  come  as 
visiting  lecturers  or  as  assimilated  instructors,  and  a  few  American 
scholars  belonged  to  the  leading  European  Academies.  Yet,  whoever 
knew  the  real  development  of  American  post-graduate  university  life, 
the  rapid  advance  of  genuine  American  scholarship,  the  incomparable 
progress  of  the  scientific  institutions  of  the  New  World,  of  their  libra- 
ries and  laboratories,  museums  and  associations,  was  well  aware  that 
Europe  had  hardly  noticed  and  certainly  not  fully  understood  the 
gigantic  strides  of  the  country  which  seemed  a  rival  only  on  commer- 
cial and  industrial  ground.  Europe  was  satisfied  with  the  traditional 
ideas  of  America's  scientific  standing  which  reflected  the  situation  of 
thirty  years  ago,  and  did  not  understand  that  the  changes  of  a  few 
lustres  mean  in  the  New  World  more  than  under  the  firmer  traditions 
of  Europe.  American  scientific  literature  was  still  neglected;  Ameri- 
can universities  treated  in  a  condescending  and  patronizing  spirit 
and  with  hardly  any  awareness  of  the  fundamental  differences  in  the 
institutions  of  the  two  sides.  Those  European  scholars  who  crossed 
the  ocean  did  it  with  missionary,  or  perhaps  with  less  unselfish,  inten- 
tions, and  the  Americans  who  attended  European  congresses  were 
mostly  treated  with  the  friendliness  which  the  self-satisfied  teacher 
shows  to  a  promising  pupil.  The  time  had  really  come  when  the  con- 
trast between  the  real  situation  and  the  traditional  construction 
became  a  danger  for  the  scientific  life  of  the  time.  Both  sides  had  to 
suffer  from  it.  The  Americans  felt  that  their  serious  and  important 
achievements  did  not  come  to  their  fullest  effectiveness  through  the 
insistent  neglect  of  those  who  by  the  tradition  of  centuries  had 
become  the  habitual  guardians  of  scientific  thought.  A  kind  of  feeling 
of  dependency  as  it  usually  develops  in  weak  colonies  too  often 
depressed  the  conscientious  scholarship  on  American  soil  as  the  result 
of  this  undue  condescension.  Yet  the  greater  harm  was  to  the  other 
side.  Once  before  Europe  had  had  the  experience  of  surprise  when 
American  successes  presented  themselves  where  nothing  of  that  kind 
was  anticipated  in  the  Old  World.  It  was  in  the  field  of  economic 
life  that  Europe  looked  down  patronizingly  on  America's  industrial 
efforts,  and  yet  before  she  was  fully  aware  how  the  change  resulted, 
suddenly  the  warning  signal  of  the  "American  danger"  was  heard 
everywhere.  The  surprise  in  the  intellectual  field  will  not  be  less. 
The  unpreparedness  was  certainly  the  same.  Of  course,  there  cannot 
be  any  danger  of  rivalry  in  the  scientific  field,  inasmuch  as  science 
knows  no  competition  but  only  cooperation.  And  yet  it  cannot  be 
without  danger  for  European  science  if  it  willfully  neglects  and  reck- 
lessly ignores  this  eager  working  of  the  modern  America.  For  both 
sides  a  change  in  the  situation  was  thus  not  only  desirable,  but  neces- 


THE  RESULTS   OF   THE   CONGRESS  133 

sary;  and  to  prepare  this  change,  to  substitute  knowledge  for  ignor- 
ance, nothing  could  have  been  more  effective  than  this  Congress  of 
Arts  and  Science. 

Even  if  we  abstract  from  the  not  inconsiderable  number  of  those 
European  scholars  who  followed  naturally  in  the  path  of  the  invited 
guests,  and  if  we  consider  merely  the  function  of  these  invited  par- 
ticipants, the  importance  of  the  procedure  is  evident.  More  than  a 
hundred  leading  scholars  from  all  European  countries  came  under 
conditions  where  academic  fellowship  on  an  equal  footing  was  a  neces- 
sary part  of  the  work.  There  was  not  the  slightest  premium  held  out 
which  might  have  attracted  them  had  not  real  interacademic  interest 
brought  them  over  the  ocean,  and  no  missionary  spirit  was  appealed 
to,  as  everything  was  equally  divided  between  American  and  foreign 
contributors.  It  was  a  real  feast  of  international  scholarship,  in 
which  the  importance  and  the  number  of  foreigners  stamped  it  as 
the  first  significant  alliance  of  the  spirit  of  learning  in  the  New  and  the 
Old  Worlds.  And  it  was  essentially  for  this  purpose  that  the  week  of 
personal  intermingling  in  St,  Louis  itself  was  preceded  and  followed 
by  happy  weeks  of  visits  to  leading  universities.  Almost  every  one 
of  those  one  hundred  European  scholars  visited  Harvard  and  Yale, 
Chicago  and  Johns  Hopkins,  Columbia  and  Pennsylvania,  saw  the 
treasures  of  Washington  and  examined  the  exhibitions  of  American 
scholarship  in  the  World's  Fair  itself.  The  change  of  opinion,  the  dis- 
appearance of  prejudice,  the  growth  of  confidence,  the  personal  inter- 
collegiate ties  which  resulted  from  all  that,  have  been  evident  since 
those  days  all  over  Europe.  And  it  is  not  surprising  that  it  is  just 
the  most  famous  and  most  important  of  the  visitors,  famous  and  im- 
portant through  their  width  and  depth  of  view,  whose  expression 
of  appreciation  and  admiration  for  the  new  achievements  has  been 
loudest. 

We  insisted  that  the  effectiveness  of  the  Congress  showed  itself  in 
two  other  directions  still :  on  the  one  side,  there  was  at  last  a  congress 
with  a  unified  programme,  a  congress  which  stood  for  a  definite 
thought,  and  which  brought  all  its  efforts  to  bear  on  the  solution  of 
one  problem.  There  seemed  a  far-reaching  agreement  of  opinion  that 
this  new  principle  of  congress  administration  had  successfully  with- 
stood the  test  of  practical  realization.  Mere  conglomerations  of  un- 
connected meetings  with  casual  programmes  and  unrelated  papers 
cannot  claim  any  longer  to  represent  the  only  possible  form  of  inter- 
national gatherings  of  scholars.  More  than  that,  their  superfluous 
and  disheartening  character  will  be  felt  in  future  more  strongly 
than  before.  No  congress  will  appear  fully  justified  whose  printed 
proceedings  do  not  show  a  real  plan  in  its  programme.  And  the 
consciousness  of  this  mission  of  the  Congress  will  certainly  be  again 
reinforced  by  the  publication  of  these  volumes,  inasmuch  as  it  is 


134       THE  SCIENTIFIC  PLAN  OF  THE  CONGRESS 

evident  that  they  represent  a  substantial  contribution  to  the  know- 
ledge of  our  time  which  would  not  have  been  made  without  the 
special  stimulating  occasion  of  the  Congress. 

And,  finally,  whether  such  a  congress  is  held  again  or  not,  the 
impulse  of  this  one  cannot  be  lost  on  account  of  the  special  end  to 
which  all  its  efforts  have  been  directed:  the  unity  of  scientific  know- 
ledge. We  had  emphasized  from  the  first  that  here  was  the  centre 
of  our  purposes  in  a  time  whose  scientific  specialization  necessarily 
involves  a  scattering  of  scholarly  work  and  which  yet  in  its  deepest 
meaning  strives  for  a  new  synthesis,  for  a  new  unity,  which  is  to  give 
to  all  this  scattered  labor  a  real  dignity  and  significance;  truly 
nothing  was  more  needed  than  an  intense  accentuation  of  the  internal 
harmony  of  all  human  knowledge.  But  for  that  it  is  not  enough  that 
the  masses  feel  instinctively  the  deep  need  of  such  unifying  move- 
ments, nor  is  it  enough  that  the  philosophers  point  with  logical  argu- 
ments towards  the  new  synthesis.  The  philosopher  can  only  stand  by 
and  point  the  way;  the  specialists  themselves  must  go  the  way.  And 
here  at  last  they  have  done  so.  Leaders  of  thought  have  interrupted 
their  specialistic  work  and  have  left  their  detailed  inquiries  to  seek 
the  fundamental  conceptions  and  methods  and  principles  which  bind 
all  knowledge  together,  and  thus  to  work  towards  that  unity  from 
which  all  special  work  derives  its  meaning.  Whether  or  not  their 
cooperation  has  produced  anything  which  is  final  is  a  question  almost 
insignificant  compared  with  the  fundamental  fact  that  they  cooper- 
ated at  all  for  this  ideal  synthetic  purpose.  This  fact  can  never  lose 
its  influence  on  the  scholarly  effort  of  our  age,  and  will  certainly  find 
its  strongest  reinforcement  in  this  unified  publication.  It  has  ful- 
filled its  noblest  purpose  if  it  adds  strength  to  the  deepest  movement 
of  our  time,  the  movement  towards  unity  of  meaning  in  the  scattered 
manifoldness  of  scientific  endeavor  with  which  the  twentieth  century 
has  opened. 


PROCEEDINGS   OF  THE   CONGRESS 


INTRODUCTORY  ADDRESS 

DELIVERED    AT   THE    OPENING    EXERCISES    AT   FESTIVAL   HALL    BY 
PROFESSOR    SIMON    NEWCOMB,    PRESIDENT    OF   THE    CONGRESS 


THE   EVOLUTION  OF   THE   SCIENTIFIC  INVESTIGATOR 

As  we  look  at  the  assemblage  gathered  in  this  hall,  comprising  so 
many  names  of  widest  renown  in.  every  branch  of  learning,  —  we 
might  almost  say  in  every  field  of  human  endeavor,  —  the  first  in- 
quiry suggested  must  be  after  the  object  of  our  meeting.  The  answer 
is,  that  our  purpose  corresponds  to  the  eminence  of  the  assemblage. 
We  aim  at  nothing  less  than  a  survey  of  the  realm  of  knowledge,  as 
comprehensive  as  is  permitted  by  the  limitations  of  time  and  space. 
The  organizers  of  our  Congress  have  honored  me  with  the  charge  of 
presenting  such  preliminary  view  of  its  field  as  may  make  clear  the 
spirit  of  our  undertaking. 

Certain  tendencies  characteristic  of  the  science  of  our  day  clearly 
suggest  the  direction  of  our  thoughts  most  appropriate  to  the  oc- 
casion. Among  the  strongest  of  these  is  one  toward  laying  greater 
stress  on  questions  of  the  beginning  of  things,  and  regarding  a  know- 
ledge of  the  laws  of  development  of  any  object  of  study  as  necessary 
to  the  understanding  of  its  present  form.  It  may  be  conceded  that 
the  principle  here  involved  is  as  applicable  in  the  broad  field  before 
us  as  in  a  special  research  into  the  properties  of  the  minutest  or- 
ganism. It  therefore  seems  meet  that  we  should  begin  by  inquir- 
ing what  agency  has  brought  about  the  remarkable  development 
of  science  to  which  the  world  of  to-day  bears  witness.  This  view  is  re- 
cognized in  the  plan  of  our  proceedings,  by  providing  for  each  great 
department  of  knowledge  a  review  of  its  progress  during  the  century 
that  has  elapsed  since  the  great  event  commemorated  by  the  scenes 
outside  this  hall.  But  such  reviews  do  not  make  up  that  general 
survey  of  science  at  large  which  is  necessary  to  the  development  of 
our  theme,  and  which  must  include  the  action  of  causes  that  had 
their  origin  long  before  our  time.    The  movement  which  culminated 


136  INTRODUCTORY  ADDRESS 

in  making  the  nineteenth  century  ever  memorable  in  history  is  the 
outcome  of  a  long  series  of  causes,  acting  through  many  centuries, 
which  are  worthy  of  especial  attention  on  such  an  occasion  as  this. 
In  setting  them  forth  we  should  avoid  laying  stress  on  those  visible 
manifestations  which,  striking  the  eye  of  every  beholder,  are  in  no 
danger  of  being  overlooked,  and  search  rather  for  those  agencies  whose 
activities  underlie  the  whole  visible  scene,  but  which  are  liable  to  be 
blotted  out  of  sight  by  the  very  brilliancy  of  the  results  to  which  they 
have  given  rise.  It  is  easy  to  draw  attention  to  the  wonderful  qualities 
of  the  oak;  but  from  that  very  fact,  it  may  be  needful  to  point  out 
that  the  real  wonder  lies  concealed  in  the  acorn  from  which  it  grew. 

Our  inquiry  into  the  logical  order  of  the  causes  which  have  made 
our  civilization  what  it  is  to-day  will  be  facilitated  by  bringing  to 
mind  certain  elementary  considerations  —  ideas  so  familiar  that 
setting  them  forth  may  seem  like  citing  a  body  of  truisms  —  and 
yet  so  frequently  overlooked,  not  only  individually,  but  in  their 
relation  to  each  other,  that  the  conclusion  to  which  they  lead  may  be 
lost  to  sight.  One  of  these  propositions  is  that  psj^chical  rather  than 
material  causes  are  those  which  we  should  regard  as  fundamental  in 
directing  the  development  of  the  social  organism.  The  human 
intellect  is  the  really  active  agent  in  every  branch  of  endeavor, — 
the  primum  mobile  of  civilization,  —  and  all  those  material  mani- 
festations to  which  our  attention  is  so  often  directed  are  to  be  re- 
garded as  secondary  to  this  first  agency.  If  it  be  true  that  "  in  the 
world  is  nothing  great  but  man;  in  man  is  nothing  great  but  mind," 
then  should  the  keynote  of  our  discourse  be  the  recognition  of  this 
first  and  greatest  of  powers. 

Another  well-known  fact  is  that  those  applications  of  the  forces 
of  nature  to  the  promotion  of  human  welfare  which  have  made  our 
age  what  it  is,  are  of  such  comparatively  recent  origin  that  we  need 
go  back  only  a  single  century  to  antedate  their  most  important  fea- 
tures, and  scarcely  more  than  four  centuries  to  find  their  beginning. 
It  follows  that  the  subject  of  our  inquiry  should  be  the  commence- 
ment, not  many  centuries  ago,  of  a  certain  new  form  of  intellectual 
activity. 

Having  gained  this  point  of  view,  our  next  inquiry'will  be  into  the 
nature  of  that  activity,  and  its  relation  to  the  stages  of  progress 
which  preceded  and  followed  its  beginning.  The  superficial  observer, 
who  sees  the  oak  but  forgets  the  acorn,  might  tell  us  that  the  special 
qualities  which  have  brought  out  such  great  results  are  expert 
scientific  knowledge  and  rare  ingenuity,  directed  to  the  application 
of  the  powers  of  steam  and  electricity.  From  this  point  of  view  the 
great  inventors  and  the  great  captains  of  industry  were  the  first 
agents  in  bringing  about  the  modern  era.  But  the  more  careful 
inquirer  will  see  that  the  work  of  these  men  was  possible  only  through 


EVOLUTION  OF   THE  SCIENTIFIC   INVESTIGATOR     137 

a  knowledge  of  the  laws  of  nature,  which  had  been  gained  by  men 
whose  work  took  precedence  of  theirs  in  logical  order,  and  that 
success  in  invention  has  been  measured  by  completeness  in  such 
knowledge.  While  giving  all  due  honor  to  the  great  inventors,  let 
us  remember  that  the  first  place  is  that  of  the  great  investigators, 
whose  forceful  intellects  opened  the  way  to  secrets  preAaously  hidden 
from  men.  Let  it  be  an  honor  and  not  a  reproach  to  these  men,  that 
they  were  not  actuated  by  the  love  of  gain,  and  did  not  keep  utilita- 
rian ends  in  view  in  the  pursuit  of  their  researches.  If  it  seems  that  in 
neglecting  such  ends  they  were  leaving  undone  the  most  important 
part  of  their  work,  let  us  remember  that  nature  turns  a  forbidding 
face  to  those  who  pay  her  court  with  the  hope  of  gain,  and  is  respons- 
ive only  to  those  suitors  whose  love  for  her  is  pure  and  undefiled. 
Not  only  is  the  special  genius  required  in  the  investigator  not  that 
generally  best  adapted  to  applying  the  discoveries  which  he  makes, 
but  the  result  of  his  having  sordid  ends  in  view  would  be  to  nar- 
row the  field  of  his  efforts,  and  exercise  a  depressing  effect  upon  his 
activities.  The  true  man  of  science  has  no  such  expression  in 
his  vocabulary  as  "useful  knowledge."  His  domain  is  as  wide 
as  nature  itself,  and  he  best  fulfills  his  mission  when  he  leaves  to 
others  the  task  of  applying  the  knowledge  he  gives  to  the  world. 

We  have  here  the  explanation  of  the  well-known  fact  that  the 
functions  of  the  investigator  of  the  laws  of  nature,  and  of  the  in- 
ventor who  applies  these  laws  to  utilitarian  purposes,  are  rarely 
united  in  the  same  person.  If  the  one  conspicuous  exception  which 
the  past  century  presents  to  this  rule  is  not  unique,  we  should  prob- 
ably have  to  go  back  to  Watt  to  find  another. 

From  this  viewpoint  it  is  clear  that  the  primary  agent  in  the 
movement  which  has  elevated  man  to  the  masterful  position  he  now 
occupies,  is  the  scientific  investigator.  He  it  is  whose  work  has  de- 
prived plague  and  pestilence  of  their  terrors,  alleviated  human  suffer- 
ing, girdled  the  earth  with  the  electric  wire,  bound  the  continent 
with  the  iron  way,  and  made  neighbors  of  the  most  distant  nations. 
As  the  first  agent  which  has  made  possible  this  meeting  of  his  re- 
presentatives, let  his  evolution  be  this  day  our  worthy  theme.  As  we 
follow  the  evolution  of  an  organism  by  studying  the  stages  of  its 
growth,  so  we  have  to  show  how  the  work  of  the  scientific  investi- 
gator is  related  to  the  ineffectual  efforts  of  his  predecessors. 

In  our  time  we  think  of  the  process  of  development  in  nature  as 
one  going  continuously  forward  through  the  combination  of  the 
opposite  processes  of  evolution  and  dissolution.  The  tendency  of  our 
thought  has  been  in  the  direction  of  banishing  cataclysms  to  the 
theological  limbo,  and  viewing  nature  as  a  sleepless  plodder,  en- 
dowed with  infinite  patience,  waiting  through  long  ages  for  results. 
I  do  not  contest  the  truth  of  the  principle  of  continuity  on  which 


138  INTRODUCTORY  ADDRESS 

this  view  is  based.  But  it  fails  to  make  known  to  us  the  whole  truth. 
The  building  of  a  ship  from  the  time  that  her  keel  is  laid  until  she  is 
making  her  way  across  the  ocean  is  a  slow  and  gradual  process;  yet 
there  is  a  cataclysmic  epoch  opening  up  a  new  era  in  her  history.  It 
is  the  moment  when,  after  lying  for  months  or  years  a  dead,  inert, 
immovable  mass,  she  is  suddenly  endowed  with  the  power  of  motion, 
and,  as  if  imbued  with  life,  glides  into  the  stream,  eager  to  begin  the 
career  for  which  she  was  designed. 

I  think  it  is  thus  in  the  development  of  humanity.  Long  ages 
may  pass  during  which  a  race,  to  all  external  observation,  appears  to 
be  making  no  real  progress.  Additions  may  be  made  to  learning,  and 
the  records  of  history  may  constantly  grow,  but  there  is  nothing  in 
its  sphere  of  thought,  or  in  the  features  of  its  life,  that  can  be  called 
essentially  new.  Yet,  nature  may  have  been  all  along  slowly  working 
in  a  way  which  evades  our  scrutiny  until  the  result  of  her  operations 
suddenly  appears  in  a  new  and  revolutionary  movement,  carrying 
the  race  to  a  higher  plane  of  civilization. 

It  is  not  difficult  to  point  out  such  epochs  in  human  progress.  The 
greatest  of  all^  because  it  was  the  first,  is  one  of  which  we  find  no 
record  either  in  written  or  geological  history.  It  was  the  epoch  when 
our  progenitors  first  took  conscious  thought  of  the  morrow,  first  used 
the  crude  weapons  which  nature  had  placed  within  their  reach  to 
kill  their  prey,  first  built  a  fire  to  warm  their  bodies  and  cook  their 
food.  I  love  to  fancy  that  there  was  some  one  first  man,  the  Adam 
of  evolution,  who  did  all  this,  and  who  used  the  power  thus  acquired 
to  show  his  fellows  how  they  might  profit  by  his  example.  When 
the  members  of  the  tribe  or  community  which  he  gathered  around 
him  began  to  conceive  of  life  as  a  whole,  —  to  include  yesterday,  to- 
day, and  to-morrow  in  the  same  mental  grasp  —  to  think  how  they 
might  apply  the  gifts  of  nature  to  their  own  uses,  —  a  movement 
was  begun  which  should  ultimately  lead  to  civilization. 

Long  indeed  must  have  been  the  ages  required  for  the  development 
of  this  rudest  primitive  community  into  the  civilization  revealed  to 
us  by  the  most  ancient  tablets  of  Egypt  and  Assyria.  After  spoken 
language  was  developed,  and  after  the  rude  representation  of  ideas 
by  visible  marks  drawn  to  resemble  them  had  long  been  practiced, 
some  Cadmus  must  have  invented  an  alphabet.  When  the  use  of 
written  language  was  thus  introduced,  the  word  of  command  ceased 
to  be  confined  to  the  range  of  the  human  voice,  and  it  became  pos- 
sible for  master  minds  to  extend  their  influence  as  far  as  a  written 
message  could  be  carried.  Then  were  communities  gathered  into 
provinces;  provinces  into  kingdoms;  kingdoms  into  the  great 
empires  of  antiquity.  Then  arose  a  stage  of  civilization  which  we 
find  pictured  in  the  most  ancient  records,  —  a  stage  in  which  men 
were  governed  by  laws  that  were  perhaps  as  wisely  adapted  to  their 


EVOLUTION  OF   THE  SCIENTIFIC  INVESTIGATOR     139 

conditions  as  our  laws  are  to  ours, — in  which  the  phenomena  of 
nature  were  rudely  observed,  and  striking  occurrences  in  the  earth 
or  in  the  heavens  recorded  in  the  annals  of  the  nation. 

Vast  was  the  progress  of  knowledge  during  the  interval  between 
these  empires  and  the  century  in  which  modern  science  began.  Yet, 
if  I  am  right  in  making  a  distinction  between  the  slow  and  regular 
steps  of  progress,  each  growing  naturally  out  of  that  which  preceded 
it,  and  the  entrance  of  the  mind  at  some  fairly  definite  epoch  into  an 
entirely  new  sphere  of  activity,  it  would  appear  that  there  was  only 
one  such  epoch  during  the  entire  interval.  This  was  when  abstract 
geometrical  reasoning  commenced,  and  astronomical  observations 
aiming  at  precision  were  recorded,  compared,  and  discussed.  Closely 
associated  with  it  must  have  been  the  construction  of  the  forms  of 
logic.  The  radical  difference  between  the  demonstration  of  a  theorem 
of  geometry  and  the  reasoning  of  every-day  life  which  the  masses  of 
men  must  have  practiced  from  the  beginning,  and  which  few  even 
to-day  ever  get  beyond,  is  so  evident  at  a  glance  that  I  need  not 
dwell  upon  it.  The  principal  feature  of  this  advance  is  that,  by  one 
of  those  antinomies  of  the  human  intellect  of  which  examples  are  not 
wanting  even  in  our  own  time,  the  development  of  abstract  ideas 
preceded  the  concrete  knowledge  of  natural  phenomena.  When  we 
reflect  that  in  the  geometry  of  EucHd  the  science  of  space  was 
brought  to  such  logical  perfection  that  even  to-day  its  teachers  are 
not  agreed  as  to  the  practicability  of  any  great  improvement  upon 
it,  we  cannot  avoid  the  feeling  that  a  very  slight  change  in  the 
direction  of  the  intellectual  activity  of  the  Greeks  would  have  led  to 
the  beginning  of  natural  science.  But  it  would  seem  that  the  very 
purity  and  perfection  which  was  aimed  at  in  their  system  of  geometry 
stood  in  the  way  of  any  extension  or  application  of  its  methods  and 
spirit  to  the  field  of  nature.  One  example  of  this  is  worthy  of  atten- 
tion. In  modern  teaching  the  idea  of  magnitude  as  generated  by 
motion  is  freely  introduced.  A  line  is  described  by  a  moving  point; 
a  plane  by  a  moving  line;  a  solid  by  a  moving  plane.  It  may,  at  first 
sight,  seem  singular  that  this  conception  finds  no  place  in  the  Euclid- 
ian system.  But  we  may  regard  the  omission  as  a  mark  of  logical 
purity  and  rigor.  Had  the  real  or  supposed  advantages  of  introduc- 
ing motion  into  geometrical  conceptions  been  suggested  to  Euclid, 
we  may  suppose  him  to  have  replied  that  the  theorems  of  space  are 
independent  of  time;  that  the  idea  of  motion  necessarily  implies 
time,  and  that,  in  consequence,  to  avail  ourselves  of  it  would  be  to 
introduce  an  extraneous  element  into  geometry. 

It  is  quite  possible  that  the  contempt  of  the  ancient  philosophers 
for  the  practical  application  of  their  science,  which  has  continued  in 
some  form  to  our  own  time,  and  which  is  not  altogether  unwholesome, 
was  a  powerful  factor  in  the  same  direction.    The  result  was  that, 


140  INTRODUCTORY  ADDRESS 

in  keeping  geometry  pure  from  ideas  which  did  not  belong  to  it,  it 
failed  to  form  what  might  otherwise  have  been  the  basis  of  physical 
science.  Its  founders  missed  the  discovery  that  methods  similar  to 
those  of  geometric  demonstration  could  be  extended  into  other  and 
wider  fields  than  that  of  space.  Thus  not  only  the  development  of 
applied  geometry,  but  the  reduction  of  other  conceptions  to  a  rigorous 
mathematical  form  was  indefinitely  postponed. 

Astronomy  is  necessarily  a  science  of  observation  pure  and  simple, 
in  which  experiment  can  have  no  place  except  as  an  auxiliary.  The 
vague  accounts  of  striking  celestial  phenomena  handed  down  by  the 
priests  and  astrologers  of  antiquity  were  followed  in  the  time  of  the 
Greeks  by  observations  having,  in  form  at  least,  a  rude  approach  to 
precision,  though  nothing  like  the  degree  of  precision  that  the  astro- 
nomer of  to-day  would  reach  with  the  naked  eye,  aided  by  such 
instruments  as  he  could  fashion  from  the  tools  at  the  command  of 
the  ancients. 

The  rude  observations  commenced  by  the  Babylonians  were 
continued  with  gradually  improving  instruments,  —  first  by  the 
Greeks  and  afterward  by  the  Arabs, — but  the  results  failed  to  afford 
any  insight  into  the  true  relation  of  the  earth  to  the  heavens.  What 
was  most  remarkable  in  this  failure  is  that,  to  take  a  first  step  forward 
which  would  have  led  on  to  success,  no  more  was  necessary  than  a 
course  of  abstract  thinking  vastly  easier  than  that  required  for  work- 
ing out  the  problems  of  geometry.  That  space  is  infinite  is  an  unex- 
pressed axiom,  tacitly  assumed  by  Euclid  and  his  successors.  Com- 
bining this  with  the  most  elementary  consideration  of  the  properties 
of  the  triangle,  it  would  be  seen  that  a  body  of  any  given  size  could 
be  placed  at  such  a  distance  in  space  as  to  appear  to  us  like  a  point. 
Hence  a  body  as  large  as  our  earth,  which  was  known  to  be  a  globe 
from  the  time  that  the  ancient  Phoenicians  navigated  the  Mediter- 
ranean, if  placed  in  the  heavens  at  a  sufficient  distance,  would  look 
like  a  star.  The  obvious  conclusion  that  the  stars  might  be  bodies 
like  our  globe,  shining  either  by  their  own  light  or  by  that  of  the  sun, 
would  have  been  a  first  step  to  the  understanding  of  the  true  system 
of  the  world. 

There  is  historic  evidence  that  this  deduction  did  not  wholly 
escape  the  Greek  thinkers.  It  is  true  that  the  critical  student  will 
assign  little  weight  to  the  current  belief  that  the  vague  theory  of 
Pythagoras  —  that  fire  was  at  the  centre  of  all  things  —  implies  a 
conception  of  the  heliocentric  theory  of  the  solar  system.  But  the 
testimony  of  Archimedes,  confused  though  it  is  in  form,  leaves  no 
serious  doubt  that  Aristarchus  of  Samos  not  only  propounded  the 
view  that  the  earth  revolves  both  on  its  own  axis  and  around  the  sun, 
but  that  he  correctly  removed  the  great  stumbling-block  in  the  way 
of  this  theory  by  adding  that  the  distance  of  the  fixed  stars  was 


EVOLUTION  OF   THE  SCIENTIFIC  INVESTIGATOR    141 

infinitely  greater  than  the  dimensions  of  the  earth's  orbit.  Even  the 
world  of  philosophy  was  not  yet  ready  for  this  conception,  and,  so  far 
from  seeing  the  reasonableness  of  the  explanation,  we  find  Ptolemy 
arguing  against  the  rotation  of  the  earth  on  grounds  which  careful 
observations  of  the  phenomena  around  him  would  have  shown  to  be 
ill-founded. 

Physical  science,  if  we  can  apply  that  term  to  an  uncoordinated 
body  of  facts,  was  successfully  cultivated  from  the  earliest  times. 
Something  must  have  been  known  of  the  properties  of  metals,  and 
the  art  of  extracting  them  from  their  ores  must  have  been  practiced, 
from  the  time  that  coins  and  medals  were  first  stamped.  The  pro- 
perties of  the  most  common  compounds  were  discovered  by  alchem- 
ists in  their  vain  search  for  the  philosopher's  stone,  but  no  actual 
progress  worthy  of  the  name  rewarded  the  practitioners  of  the  black 
art. 

Perhaps  the  first  approach  to  a  correct  method  was  that  of  Archi- 
medes, who  by  much  thinking  worked  out  the  law  of  the  lever, 
reached  the  conception  of  the  centre  of  gravity,  and  demonstrated 
the  first  principles  of  hydrostatics.  It  is  remarkable  that  he  did  not 
extend  his  researches  into  the  phenomena  of  motion,  whether  spon- 
taneous or  produced  by  force.  The  stationary  condition  of  the  human 
intellect  is  most  strikingly  illustrated  by  the  fact  that  not  until  the 
time  of  Leonardo  was  any  substantial  advance  made  on  his  discovery. 
To  sum  up  in  one  sentence  the  most  characteristic  feature  of  ancient 
and  medieval  science,  we  see  a  notable  contrast  between  the  precision 
of  thought  implied  in  the  construction  and  demonstration  of  geo- 
metrical theorems  and  the  vague  indefinite  character  of  the  ideas  of 
natural  phenomena  generally,  a  contrast  which  did  not  disappear 
until  the  foundations  of  modern  science  began  to  be  laid. 

We  should  miss  the  most  essential  point  of  the  difference  between 
medieval  and  modern  learning  if  we  looked  upon  it  as  mainly  a  differ- 
ence either  in  the  precision  or  the  amount  of  knowledge.  The  devel- 
opment of  both  of  these  qualities  would,  under  any  circumstances, 
have  been  slow  and  gradual,  but  sure.  We  .can  hardly  suppose  that 
any  one  generation,  or  even  any  one  century,  would  have  seen  the 
complete  substitution  of  exact  for  inexact  ideas.  Slowness  of  growth 
is  as  inevitable  in  the  case  of  knowledge  as  in  that  of  a  growing  organ- 
ism. The  most  essential  point  of  difference  is  one  of  those  seemingly 
slight  ones,  the  importance  of  which  we  are  too  apt  to  overlook.  It 
was  like  the  drop  of  blood  in  the  wrong  place,  which  some  one  has 
told  us  makes  all  the  difference  between  a  philosopher  and  a  maniac. 
It  was  all  the  difference  between  a  living  tree  and  a  dead  one,  between 
an  inert  mass  and  a  growing  organism.  The  transition  of  knowledge 
from  the  dead  to  the  living  form  must,  in  any  complete  review  of  the 
subject,  be  looked  upon  as  the  really  great  event  of  modern  times. 


142  INTRODUCTORY  ADDRESS 

Before  this  event  the  intellect  was  bound  down  by  a  scholasticism 
which  regarded  knowledge  as  a  rounded  whole,  the  parts  of  which 
were  written  in  books  and  carried  in  the  minds  of  learned  men.  The 
student  was  taught  from  the  beginning  of  his  work  to  look  upon 
authority  as  the  foundation  of  his  beliefs.  The  older  the  authority  the 
greater  the  weight  it  carried.  So  effective  was  this  teaching  that  it 
seems  never  to  have  occurred  to  individual  men  that  they  had  all  the 
opportunities  ever  enjoyed  by  Aristotle  of  discovering  truth,  with  the 
added  advantage  of  all  his  knowledge  to  begin  with.  Advanced  as 
was  the  development  of  formal  logic,  that  practical  logic  was  wanting 
which  could  see  that  the  last  of  a  series  of  authorities,  every  one  of 
which  rested  on  those  which  preceded  it,  could  never  form  a  surer 
foundation  for  any  doctrine  than  that  supplied  by  its  original  pro- 
pounder. 

The  result  of  this  view  of  knowledge  was  that,  although  during  the 
fifteen  centuries  following  the  death  of  the  geometer  of  Syracuse 
great  universities  were  founded  at  which  generations  of  professors 
expounded  all  the  learning  of  their  time,  neither  professor  nor  student 
ever  suspected  what  latent  possibilities  of  good  were  concealed  in  the 
most  familiar  operations  of  nature.  Every  one  felt  the  wind  blow,  saw 
water  boil,  and  heard  the  thunder  crash,  but  never  thought  of  inves- 
tigating the  forces  here  at  play.  Up  to  the  middle  of  the  fifteenth 
century  the  most  acute  observer  could  scarcely  have  seen  the  dawn 
of  a  new  era. 

In  view  of  this  state  of  things,  it  must  be  regarded  as  one  of  the  most 
remarkable  facts  in  evolutionary  history  that  four  or  five  men,  whose 
mental  constitution  was  either  typical  of  the  new  order  of  things  or 
who  were  powerful  agents  in  bringing  it  about,  were  all  born  during 
the  fifteenth  century,  four  of  them  at  least  at  so  nearly  the  same  time 
as  to  be  contemporaries. 

Leonardo  da  Vinci,  whose  artistic  genius  has  charmed  succeeding 
generations,  was  also  the  first  practical  engineer  of  his  time,  and  the 
first  man  after  Archimedes  to  make  a  substantial  advance  in  develop- 
ing the  laws  of  motion.  That  the  world  was  not  prepared  to  make 
use  of  his  scientific  discoveries  does  not  detract  from  the  significance 
which  must  attach  to  the  period  of  his  birth. 

Shortly  after  him  was  born  the  great  navigator  whose  bold  spirit 
was  to  make  known  a  new  world,  thus  giving  to  commercial  enterprise 
that  impetus  which  was  so  powerful  an  agent  in  bringing  about  a 
revolution  in  the  thoughts  of  men. 

The  birth  of  Columbus  was  soon  followed  by  that  of  Copernicus, 
the  first  after  Aristarchus  to  demonstrate  the  true  system  of  the 
world.  In  him  more  than  in  any  of  his  contemporaries  do  we  see  the 
struggle  between  the  old  forms  of  thought  and  the  new.  It  seems 
almost  pathetic  and  is  certainly  most  suggestive  of  the  general  view 


EVOLUTION  OF   THE  SCIENTIFIC  INVESTIGATOR    143 

of  knowledge  taken  at  that  time  that,  instead  of  claiming  credit  for 
bringing  to  light  great  truths  before  unknown,  he  made  a  labored 
attempt  to  show  that,  after  all,  there  was  nothing  really  new  in  his 
system,  which  he  claimed  to  date  from  Pythagoras  and  Philolaus. 
In  this  connection  it  is  curious  that  he  makes  no  mention  of  Aris- 
tarchus,  who  I  think  will  be  regarded  by  conservative  historians  as 
his  only  demonstrated  predecessor.  To  the  hold  of  the  older  ideas 
upon  his  mind  we  must  attribute  the  fact  that  in  constructing  his 
system  he  took  great  pains  to  make  as  little  change  as  possible  in 
ancient  conceptions. 

Luther,  the  greatest  thought-stirrer  of  them  all,  practically  of  the 
same  generation  with  Copernicus,  Leonardo,  and  Columbus,  does  not 
come  in  as  a  scientific  investigator,  but  as  the  great  loosener  of  chains 
which  had  so  fettered  the  intellect  of  men  that  they  dared  not  think 
otherwise  than  as  the  authorities  thought. 

Almost  coeval  with  the  advent  of  these  intellects  was  the  invention 
of  printing  with  movable  type.  Gutenberg  was  born  during  the  first 
decade  of  the  century,  and  his  associates  and  others  credited  with  the 
invention  not  many  years  afterward.  If  we  accept  the  principle  on 
which  I  am  basing  my  argument,  that  we  should  assign  the  first  place 
to  the  birth  of  those  psychic  agencies  which  started  men  on  new  lines 
of  thought,  then  surely  was  the  fifteenth  the  wonderful  century. 

Let  us  not  forget  that,  in  assigning  the  actors  then  born  to  their 
places,  we  are  not  narrating  history,  but  studying  a  special  phase  of 
evolution.  It  matters  not  for  us  that  no  university  invited  Leonardo 
to  its  halls,  and  that  his  science  was  valued  by  his  contemporaries 
only  as  an  adjunct  to  the  art  of  engineering.  The  great  fact  still  is 
that  he  was  the  first  of  mankind  to  propound  laws  of  motion.  It  is 
not  for  anything  in  Luther's  doctrines  that  he  finds  a  place  in  our 
scheme.  No  matter  for  us  whether  they  were  sound  or  not.  What  he 
did  toward  the  evolution  of  the  scientific  investigator  was  to  show  by 
his  example  that  a  man  might  question  the  best-established  and  most 
venerable  authority  and  still  live  —  still  preserve  his  intellectual 
integrity  —  still  command  a  hearing  from  nations  and  their  rulers. 
It  matters  not  for  us  whetJier  Columbus  ever  knew  that  he  had  dis- 
covered a  new  continent.  His  work  was  to  teach  that  neither  hydra, 
chimera,  nor  abyss  —  neither  divine  injunction  nor  infernal  machina- 
tion —  was  in  the  way  of  men  visiting  every  part  of  the  globe,  and 
that  the  problem  of  conquering  the  world  reduced  itself  to  one  of 
sails  and  rigging,  hull  and  compass.  The  better  part  of  Copernicus 
was  to  direct  man  to  a  viewpoint  whence  he  should  see  that  the 
heavens  were  of  like  matter  with  the  earth.  All  this  done,  the  acorn 
was  planted  from  which  the  oak  of  our  civilization  should  spring. 
The  mad  quest  for  gold  which  followed  the  discovery  of  Columbus, 
the  questionings  w^hich  absorbed  the  attention  of  the  learned,  the 


144  INTRODUCTORY  ADDRESS 

indignation  excited  by  the  seeming  vagaries  of  a  Paracelsus,  the  fear 
and  trembhng  lest  the  strange  doctrine  of  Copernicus  should  under- 
mine the  faith  of  centuries,  were  all  helps  to  the  germination  of  the 
seed  —  stimuli  to  thought  which  urged  it  on  to  explore  the  new  fields 
opened  up  to  its  occupation.  This  given,  all  that  has  since  followed 
came  out  in  regular  order  of  development,  and  need  be  here  con- 
sidered only  in  those  phases  having  a  special  relation  to  the  purpose 
of  our  present  meeting. 

So  slow  was  the  growth  at  first  that  the  sixteenth  century  may 
scarcely  have  recognized  the  inauguration  of  a  new  era.  Torricelli 
and  Benedetti  were  of  the  third  generation  after  Leonardo,  and 
Galileo,  the  first  to  make  a  substantial  advance  upon  his  theory,  was 
born  more  than  a  century  after  him.  Only  two  or  three  men  appeared 
in  a  generation  who,  working  alone,  could  make  real  progress  in  dis- 
covery, and  even  these  could  do  little  in  leavening  the  minds  of  their 
fellow  men  with  the  new  ideas. 

Up  to  the  middle  of  the  seventeenth  century  an  agent  which  all 
experience  since  that  time  shows  to  be  necessary  to  the  most  pro- 
ductive intellectual  activity  was  wanting.  This  was  the  attraction  of 
like  minds,  making  suggestions  to  each  other,  criticising,  comparing, 
and  reasoning.  This  element  was  introduced  by  the  organization  of 
the  Royal  Society  of  London  and  the  Academy  of  Sciences  of  Paris. 

The  members  of  these  two  bodies  seem  like  ingenious  youth  sud- 
denly thrown  into  a  new  world  of  interesting  objects,  the  purposes  and 
relations  of  which  they  had  to  discover.  The  novelty  of  the  situation 
is  strikingly  shown  in  the  questions  which  occupied  the  minds  of  the 
incipient  investigators.  One  natural  result  of  British  maritime  enter- 
prise was  that  the  aspirations  of  the  Fellows  of  the  Royal  Society 
were  not  confined  to  any  continent  or  hemisphere.  Inquiries  were 
sent  all  the  way  to  Batavia  to  know  "whether  there  be  a  hill  in 
Sumatra  which  burneth  continually,  and  a  fountain  which  runneth 
pure  balsam."  The  astronomical  precision  with  which  it  seemed  pos- 
sible that  physiological  operations  might  go  on  was  evinced  by  the 
inquiry  whether  the  Indians  can  so  prepare  that  stupefying  herb 
Datura  that  "  they  make  it  lie  several  days,  months,  years,  according 
as  they  will,  in  a  man's  body  without  doing  him  any  harm,  and  at 
the  end  kill  him  without  missing  an  hour's  time."  Of  this  continent 
one  of  the  inquiries  was  whether  there  be  a  tree  in  Mexico  that  yields 
water,  wine,  vinegar,  milk,  honey,  wax,  thread,  and  needles. 

Among  the  problems  before  the  Paris  Academy  of  Sciences  those 
of  physiology  and  biology  took  a  prominent  place.  The  distillation 
of  compounds  had  long  been  practiced,  and  the  fact  that  the  more 
spirituous  elements  of  certain  substances  were  thus  separated  nat- 
urally led  to  the  question  whether  the  essential  essences  of  life  might 
not  be  discoverable  in  the  same  way.   In  order  that  all  might  par- 


EVOLUTION  OF   THE  SCIENTIFIC  INVESTIGATOR     145 

ticipate  in  the  experiments,  they  were  conducted  in  open  session  of 
the  Academy,  thus  guarding  against  the  danger  of  any  one  member 
obtaining  for  his  exclusive  personal  use  a  possible  elixir  of  life.  A 
wide  range  of  the  animal  and  vegetable  kingdom,  including  cats,  dogs, 
and  birds  of  various  species,  were  thus  analyzed.  The  practice  of 
dissection  was  introduced  on  a  large  scale.  That  of  the  cadaver  of  an 
elephant  occupied  several  sessions,  and  was  of  such  interest  that  the 
monarch  himself  was  a  spectator. 

To  the  same  epoch  with  the  formation  and  first  work  of  these  two 
bodies  belongs  the  invention  of  a  mathematical  method  which  in  its 
importance  to  the  advance  of  exact  science  may  be  classed  with  the 
invention  of  the  alphabet  in  its  relation  to  the  progress  of  society  at 
large.  The  use  of  algebraic  symbols  to  represent  quantities  had  its 
origin  before  the  commencement  of  the  new  era,  and  gradually  grew 
into  a  highly  developed  form  during  the  first  two  centuries  of  that 
era.  But  this  method  could  represent  quantities  only  as  fixed.  It  is 
true  that  the  elasticity  inherent  in  the  use  of  such  symbols  permitted 
of  their  being  applied  to  any  and  every  quantity;  yet,  in  any  one 
application,  the  quantity  was  considered  as  fixed  and  definite.  But 
most  of  the  magnitudes  of  nature  are  in  a  state  of  continual  variation; 
indeed,  since  all  motion  is  variation,  the  latter  is  a  universal  charac- 
teristic of  all  phenomena.  No  serious  advance  could  be  made  in  the 
application  of  algebraic  language  to  the  expression  of  physical  phe- 
nomena until  it  could  be  so  extended  as  to  express  variation  in  quan- 
tities, as  well  as  the  quantities  themselves.  This  extension,  worked 
out  independently  by  Newton  and  Leibnitz,  may  be  classed  as  the 
most  fruitful  of  conceptions  in  exact  science.  With  it  the  way  was 
opened  for  the  unimpeded  and  continually  accelerated  progress  of  the 
last  two  centuries. 

The  feature  of  this  period  which  has  the  closest  relation  to  the 
purpose  of  our  coming  together  is  the  seemingly  unending  subdivision 
of  knowledge  into  specialties,  many  of  which  are  becoming  so  minute 
and  so  isolated  that  they  seem  to  have  no  interest  for  any  but  their 
few  pursuers.  Happily  science  itself  has  afforded  a  corrective  for  its 
own  tendency  in  this  direction.  The  careful  thinker  will  see  that  in 
these  seemingly  diverging  branches  common  elements  and  common 
principles  are  coming  more  and  more  to  light.  There  is  an  increasing 
recognition  of  methods  of  research,  and  of  deduction,  which  are  com- 
mon to  large  branches,  or  to  the  whole  of  science.  We  are  more  and 
more  recognizing  the  principle  that  progress  in  knowledge  implies  its 
reduction  to  more  exact  forms,  and  the  expression  of  its  ideas  in 
language  more  or  less  mathematical.  The  problem  before  the  organ- 
izers of  this  Congress  was,  therefore,  to  bring  the  sciences  together, 
and  seek  for  the  unity  which  we  believe  underlies  their  infinite 
diversity. 


146  INTRODUCTORY  ADDRESS 

The  assembling  of  such  a  body  as  now  fills  this  hall  was  scarcely 
possible  in  any  preceding  generation,  and  is  made  possible  now  only 
through  the  agency  of  science  itself.  It  differs  from  all  preceding  inter- 
national meetings  by  the  universality  of  its  scope,  which  aims  to 
include  the  whole  of  knowledge.  It  is  also  unique  in  that  none  but 
leaders  have  been  sought  out  as  members.  It  is  unique  in  that  so 
many  lands  have  delegated  their  choicest  intellects  to  carry  on  its 
work.  They  come  from  the  country  to  which  our  republic  is  indebted 
for  a  third  of  its  territory,  including  the  ground  on  which  we  stand; 
from  the  land  which  has  taught  us  that  the  most  scholarly  devotion  to 
the  languages  and  learning  of  the  cloistered  past  is  compatible  with 
leadership  in  the  practical  application  of  modern  science  to  the  arts 
of  life;  from  the  island  whose  language  and  literature  have  found 
a  new  field  and  a  vigorous  growth  in  this  region;  from  the  last  seat 
of  the  holy  Roman  Empire;  from  the  country  which,  remembering 
a  monarch  who  made  an  astronomical  observation  at  the  Greenwich 
Observatory,  has  enthroned  science  in  one  of  the  highest  places  in  its 
government;  from  the  peninsula  so  learned  that  we  have  invited  one 
of  its  scholars  to  come  and  tell  us  of  our  own  language;  from  the  land 
which  gave  birth  to  Leonardo,  Galileo,  Torricelli,  Columbus,  Volta  — 
what  an  array  of  immortal  names! — from  the  little  republic  of 
glorious  history  which,  breeding  men  rugged  as  its  eternal  snow- 
peaks,  has  yet  been  the  seat  of  scientific  investigation  since  the  day  of 
the  Bernoullis;  from  the  land  whose  heroic  dwellers  did  not  hesitate 
to  use  the  ocean  itself  to  protect  it  against  invaders,  and  which  now 
makes  us  marvel  at  the  amount  of  erudition  compressed  within  its 
little  area;  from  the  nation  across  the  Pacific,  which,  by  half  a  cen- 
tury of  unequaled  progress  in  the  arts  of  life,  has  made  an  important 
contribution  to  evolutionary  science  through  demonstrating  the 
falsity  of  the  theory  that  the  most  ancient  races  are  doomed  to  be 
left  in  the  rear  of  the  advancing  age  —  in  a  word,  from  every  great 
centre  of  intellectual  activity  on  the  globe  I  see  before  me  eminent 
representatives  of  that  world-advance  in  knowledge  which  we  have 
met  to  celebrate.  May  we  not  confidently  hope  that  the  discussions 
of  such  an  assemblage  will  prove  pregnant  of  a  future  for  science 
which  shall  outshine  even  its  brilliant  past? 

Gentlemen  and  scholars  all!  You  do  not  visit  our  shores  to  find 
great  collections  in  which  centuries  of  humanity  have  given  expression 
on  canvas  and  in  marble  to  their  hopes,  fears,  and  aspirations.  Nor 
do  you  expect  institutions  and  buildings  hoary  with  age.  But  as  you 
feel  the  vigor  latent  in  the  fresh  air  of  these  expansive  prairies,  which 
has  collected  the  products  of  human  genius  by  which  we  are  here 
surrounded,  and,  I  may  add,  brought  us  together;  as  you  study  the 
institutions  which  we  have  founded  for  the  benefit,  not  only  of  our 
own  people,  but  of  humanity  at  large;  as  you  meet  the  men  who,  in 


EVOLUTION   OF   THE  SCIENTIFIC  INVESTIGATOR     147 

the  short  space  of  one  century,  have  transformed  this  valley  from  a 
savage  wilderness  into  what  it  is  to-day  —  then  may  you  find  com- 
pensation for  the  want  of  a  past  like  yours  by  seeing  with  prophetic 
eye  a  future  world-power  of  which  this  region  shall  be  the  seat.  If  such 
is  to  be  the  outcome  of  the  institutions  which  we  are  now  building  up, 
then  may  your  present  visit  be  a  blessing  both  to  your  posterity  and 
ours  by  making  that  power  one  for  good  to  all  mankind.  Your  deliber- 
ations will  help  to  demonstrate  to  us  and  to  the  world  at  large  that  the 
reign  of  law  must  supplant  that  of  brute  force  in  the  relations  of  the 
nations,  just  as  it  has  supplanted  it  in  the  relations  of  individuals. 
You  "udll  help  to  show  that  the  war  which  science  is  now  waging 
against  the  sources  of  diseases,  pain,  and  misery  offers  an  even  nobler 
field  for  the  exercise  of  heroic  qualities  than  can  that  of  battle.  We 
hope  that  when,  after  your  all  too  fleeting  sojourn  in  our  midst,  you 
return  to  your  own  shores,  you  will  long  feel  the  influence  of  the  new 
air  you  have  breathed  in  an  infusion  of  increased  vigor  in  pursuing 
your  varied  labors.  And  if  a  new  impetus  is  thus  given  to  the  great 
intellectual  movement  of  the  past  century,  resulting  not  only  in 
promoting  the  unification  of  knowledge,  but  in  widening  its  field 
through  new  combinations  of  effort  on  the  part  of  its  votaries,  the 
projectors,  organizers,  and  supporters  of  this  Congress  of  Arts  and 
Science  wiU  be  justified  of  their  labors. 


DIVISION  A  — NORMATIVE    SCIENCE 


DIVISION  A  — NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 


Speaker  :  Professor  Josiah  Royce,  Harvard  University 
{Hall  6,  September  20,  10  a.  m.) 


THE  SCIENCES  OF  THE  IDEAL 

BY  JOSIAH  ROYCE 

[Josiah  Royce,  Professor  of  History  of  Philosophy,  Harvard  University,  since 
1892.  b.  Grass  Valley,  Nevada  County,  California,  November  20,  1855. 
A.B,  University  of  California,  1875;  Ph.D.  Johns  Hopkins,  1878;  LL.D. 
University  of  Aberdeen,  Scotland;  LL.D.  Johns  Hopkins.  Instructor  in 
English  Literature  and  Logic,  University  of  California,  1878-82.  Instruct- 
or and  Assistant  Professor,  Harvard  University,  1882-92.  Author  of  Re- 
ligious Aspect  of  Philosophy;  History  of  California;  The  Feud  of  Oak  field 
Creek;  The  Spirit  of  Modern  Philosophy;  Studies  of  Good  and  Evil;  The 
World  and  the  Individual ;  Gifford  Lectures ;  and  numerous  other  works  and 
memoirs.] 

I  SHALL  not  attempt,  in  this  address,  either  to  justify  or  to  criticise 
the  name,  normative  science,  under  which  the  doctrines  which  con- 
stitute this  division  are  grouped.  It  is  enough  for  my  purpose  to 
recognize  at  the  outset  that  I  am  required,  by  the  plans  of  this  Con- 
gress, to  explain  what  scientific  interests  seem  to  me  to  be  common 
to  the  work  of  the  philosophers  and  of  the  mathematicians.  The 
task  is  one  which  makes  severe  demands  upon  the  indulgence  of  the 
listener,  and  upon  the  expository  powers  of  the  speaker,  but  it  is  a 
task  for  which  the  present  age  has  well  prepared  the  way.  The  spirit 
which  Descartes  and  Leibnitz  illustrated  seems  likely  soon  to  become, 
in  a  new  and  higher  sense,  prominent  in  science.  The  mathematicians 
are  becoming  more  and  more  philosophical.  The  philosophers,  in  the 
near  future,  will  become,  I  believe,  more  and  more  mathematical. 
It  is  my  office  to  indicate,  as  well  as  the  brief  time  and  my  poor  powers 
may  permit,  why  this  ought  to  be  so. 

To  this  end  I  shall  first  point  out  what  is  that  most  general  com- 
munity of  interest  which  unites  all  the  sciences  that  belong  to  our 
division.  Then  I  shall  indicate  what  type  of  recent  and  special 
scientific  work  most  obviously  bears  upon  the  tasks  of  all  of  us  alike. 
Thirdly,  I  shall  state  some  results  and  problems  to  which  this  type 
of  scientific  work  has  given  rise,  and  shall  try  to  show  what  promise 
we  have  of  an  early  increase  of  insight  regarding  our  common  interests. 


152  NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 

I 

The  most  general  community  of  interest  which  unites  the  various 
scientific  activities  that  belong  to  our  division  is  this:  We  are  all 
concerned  with  what  may  be  called  ideal  truth,  as  distinct  from 
physical  truth.  Some  of  us  also  have  a  strong  interest  in  physical 
truth;  but  none  of  us  lack  a  notable  and  scientific  concern  for  the 
realm  of  ideas,  viewed  as  ideas. 

Let  me  explain  what  I  mean  by  these  terms.  Whoever  studies 
physical  truth  (taking  that  term  in  its  most  general  sense)  seeks  to 
observe,  to  collate,  and,  in  the  end,  to  control,  facts  which  he  regards 
as  external  to  his  own  thought.  But  instead  of  thus  looking  mainly 
without,  it  is  possible  for  a  man  chiefly  to  take  account,  let  us  say, 
of  the  consequences  of  his  own  hypothetical  assumptions  —  assump- 
tions which  may  possess  but  a  very  remote  relation  to  the  physical 
world.  Or  again,  it  is  possible  for  such  a  student  to  be  mainly  de- 
voted to  reflecting  upon  the  formal  validity  of  his  own  inferences,  or 
upon  the  meaning  of  his  own  presuppositions,  or  upon  the  value  and 
the  interrelation  of  human  ideals.  Any  such  scientific  work,  reflective, 
considerate  principally  of  the  thinker's  own  constructions  and  pur- 
poses, or  of  the  constructions  and  purposes  of  humanity  in  general, 
is  a  pursuit  of  ideal  truth.  The  searcher  who  is  mainly  devoted  to 
the  inquiry  into  what  he  regards  as  external  facts,  is  indeed  active; 
but  his  activity  is  moulded  by  an  order  of  existence  which  he  conceives 
as  complete  apart  from  his  activity.  He  is  thoughtful;  but  a  power 
not  himself  assigns  to  him  the  problems  about  which  he  thinks.  He 
is  guided  by  ideals;  but  his  principal  ideal  takes  the  form  of  an  ac- 
ceptance of  the  world  as  it  is,  independently  of  his  ideals.  His  deal- 
ings are  with  nature.  His  aim  is  the  conquest  of  a  foreign  realm. 
But  the  student  of  what  may  be  called,  in  general  terms,  ideal  truth, 
while  he  is  devoted  as  his  fellow,  the  observer  of  outer  nature,  to 
the  general  purpose  of  being  faithful  to  the  verity  as  he  finds  it,  is 
still  aware  that  his  own  way  of  finding,  or  his  own  creative  activity 
as  an  inventor  of  hypotheses,  or  his  own  powers  of  inference,  or  his 
conscious  ideals,  constitute  in  the  main  the  object  into  which  he  is 
inquiring,  and  so  form  an  essential  aspect  of  the  sort  of  verity  which 
he  is  endeavoring  to  discover.  The  guide,  then,  of  such  a  student  is, 
in  a  peculiar  sense,  his  OAvn  reason.  His  goal  is  the  comprehension  of 
his  own  meaning,  the  conscious  and  thoughtful  conquest  of  himself. 
His  great  enemy  is  not  the  mystery  of  outer  nature,  but  the  imper- 
fection of  his  reflective  powers.  He  is,  indeed,  as  unwilling  as  is  any 
scientific  worker  to  trust  private  caprices.  He  feels  as  little  as  does 
the  observer  of  outer  facts,  that  he  is  merely  noting  down,  as  they 
pass,  the  chance  products  of  his  arbitrary  fantasy.  For  him,  as  for 
any  scientific  student,  truth  is  indeed  objective;  and  the  standards 


THE  SCIENCES  OF  THE  IDEAL  153 

to  which  he  conforms  are  eternal.  But  his  method  is  that  of  an  inner 
considerateness  rather  than  of  a  curiosity  about  external  phenomena. 
His  objective  world  is  at  the  same  time  an  essentially  ideal  world, 
and  the  eternal  verity  in  whose  light  he  seeks  to  live  has,  throughout 
his  undertakings,  a  peculiarly  intimate  relation  to  the  purposes  of 
his  own  constructive  will. 

One  may  then  sum  up  the  difference  of  attitude  which  is  here  in 
question  by  saying  that,  while  the  student  of  outer  nature  is  ex- 
plicitly conforming  his  plans  of  action,  his  ideas,  his  ideals,  to  an 
order  of  truth  which  he  takes  to  be  foreign  to  himself  —  the  student 
of  the  other  sort  of  truth,  here  especially  in  question,  is  attempting 
to  understand  his  own  plans  of  action,  that  is,  to  develop  his  ideas, 
or  to  define  his  ideals,  or  else  to  do  both  these  things. 

Now  it  is  not  hard  to  see  that  this  search  for  some  sort  of  ideal 
truth  is  indeed  characteristic  of  every  one  of  the  investigations 
which  have  been  grouped  together  in  our  division  of  the  normative 
sciences.  Pure  mathematics  shares  in  common  with  philosophy 
this  type  of  scientific  interest  in  ideal,  as  distinct  from  physical  or 
phenomenal  truth.  There  is,  to  be  sure,  a  marked  contrast  between 
the  ways  in  which  the  mathematician  and  the  philosopher  approach, 
select,  and  elaborate  their  respective  sorts  of  problems.  But  there 
is  also  a  close  relation  between  the  two  types  of  investigation  in 
question.  Let  us  next  consider  both  the  contrast  and  the  analogy  in 
some  of  their  other  most  general  features. 

Pure  mathematics  is  concerned  with  the  investigation  of  the  logical 
consequences  of  certain  exactly  stateable  postulates  or  hypotheses  — 
such,  for  instance,  as  the  postulates  upon  which  arithmetic  and  analy- 
sis are  founded,  or  such  as  the  postulates  that  he  at  the  basis  of  any 
type  of  geometry.  For  the  pure  mathematician,  the  truth  of  these 
hypotheses  or  postulates  depends,  not  upon  the  fact  that  physical 
nature  contains  phenomena  answering  to  the  postulates,  but  solely 
upon  the  fact  that  the  mathematician  is  able,  with  rational  consist- 
ency, to  state  these  assumed  first  principles,  and  to  develop  their 
consequences.  Dedekind,  in  his  famous  essay,  "  Was  Sind  und  Was 
Sollen  die  Zahlen,"  called  the  whole  numbers  "  freie  Schopfungen  des 
Menschlichen  Geistes;  "  and,  in  fact,  we  need  not  enter  into  any  dis- 
cussion of  the  psychology  of  our  number  concept  in  order  to  be  able 
to  assert  that,  however  we  men  first  came  by  our  conception  of  the 
whole  numbers,  for  the  mathematician  the  theory  of  numerical  truth 
must  appear  simply  as  the  logical  development  of  the  consequences 
of  a  few  fundamental  j&rst  principles,  such  as  those  which  Dedekind 
himself,  or  Peano,  or  other  recent  writers  upon  this  topic,  have,  in 
various  forms,  stated.  A  similar  formal  freedom  marks  the  develop- 
ment of  any  other  theory  in  the  realm  of  pure  mathematics.  Pure 
geometry,  from  the  modern  point  of  view,  is  neither  a  doctrine  forced 


154  NORMATIVE   SCIENCE 

upon  the  human  mind  by  the  constitution  of  any  primal  form  of 
intuition,  nor  yet  a  branch  of  physical  science,  limited  to  describing 
the  spatial  arrangement  of  phenomena  in  the  external  world.  Pure 
geometry  is  the  theory  of  the  consequences  of  certain  postulates 
which  the  geometer  is  at  liberty  consistently  to  make;  so  that  there 
are  as  many  types  of  geometry  as  there  are  consistent  systems  of 
postulates  of  that  generic  type  of  which  the  geometer  takes  account. 
As  is  also  now  well  known,  it  has  long  been  impossible  to  define  pure 
mathematics  as  the  science  of  quantity,  or  to  limit  the  range  of  the 
exactly  stateable  hypotheses  or  postulates  with  which  the  mathema- 
tician deals  to  the  world  of  those  objects  which,  ideally  speaking, 
can  be  viewed  as  measurable.  For  the  ideally  defined  measurable 
objects  are  by  no  means  the  only  ones  whose  properties  can  be  stated 
in  the  form  of  exact  postulates  or  hypotheses;  and  the  possible  range 
of  pure  mathematics,  if  taken  in  the  abstract,  and  viewed  apart  from 
any  question  as  to  the  value  of  given  lines  of  research,  appears  to  be 
identical  with  the  whole  realm  of  the  consequences  of  exactly  state- 
able ideal  hypotheses  of  every  type. 

One  limitation  must,  however,  be  mentioned,  to  which  the  asser- 
tion just  made  is,  in  practice,  obviously  subject.  And  this  is,  indeed, 
a  momentous  limitation.  The  exactly  stated  ideal  hypotheses  whose 
consequences  the  mathematician  develops  must  possess,  as  is  some- 
times said,  sufiicient  intrinsic  importance  to  be  worthy  of  scientific 
treatment.  They  must  not  be  trivial  hypotheses.  The  mathema- 
tician is  not,  like  the  solver  of  chess  problems,  merely  displaying 
his  skill  in  dealing  with  the  arbitrary  fictions  of  an  ideal  game.  His 
truth  is,  indeed,  ideal;  his  world  is,  indeed,  treated  by  his  science  as 
if  this  world  were  the  creation  of  his  postulates  a  "  freie  Schopfung." 
But  he  does  not  thus  create  for  mere  sport.  On  the  contrary,  he  re- 
ports a  significant  order  of  truth.  As  a  fact,  the  ideal  systems  of  the 
pure  mathematician  are  customarily  defined  with  an  obvious,  even 
though  often  highly  abstract  and  remote,  relation  to  the  structure 
of  our  ordinary  empirical  world.  Thus  the  various  algebras  which 
have  been  actually  developed  have,  in  the  main,  definite  relations 
to  the  structure  of  the  space  world  of  our  physical  experience.  The 
different  systems  of  ideal  geometry,  even  in  all  their  ideality,  still 
cluster,  so  to  speak,  about  the  suggestions  which  our  daily  experi- 
ence of  space  and  of  matter  give  us.  Yet  I  suppose  that  no  mathe- 
matician would  be  disposed,  at  the  present  time,  to  accept  any  brief 
definition  of  the  degree  of  closeness  or  remoteness  of  relation  to  or- 
dinary experience  which  shall  serve  to  distinguish  a  trivial  from 
a  genuinely  significant  branch  of  mathematical  theory.  In  general,  a 
mathematician  who  is  devoted  to  the  theory  of  functions,  or  to  group 
theory,  appears  to  spend  little  time  in  attempting  to  show  why  the 
development  of  the  consequences  of  his  postulates  is  a  significant 


THE  SCIENCES  OF  THE  IDEAL  155 

enterprise.  The  concrete  mathematical  interest  of  his  inquiry  sustains 
him  in  his  labors,  and  wins  for  him  the  sympathy  of  his  fellows.  To 
the  questions,  "  Why  consider  the  ideal  structure  of  just  this  system 
of  object  at  all?  "  "  Why  study  various  sorts  of  numbers,  or  the 
properties  of  functions,  or  of  groups,  or  the  system  of  points  in 
projective  geometry?  "  —  the  pure  mathematician  in  general,  cares 
to  reply  only,  that  the  topic  of  his  special  investigation  appears  to 
him  to  possess  sufficient  mathematical  interest.  The  freedom  of  his 
science  thus  justifies  his  enterprise.  Yet,  as  I  just  pointed  out,  this 
freedom  is  never  mere  caprice.  This  ideal  interest  is  not  without  a 
general  relation  to  the  concerns  even  of  common  sense.  In  brief,  as 
it  seems  at  once  fair  to  say,  the  pure  mathematician  is  working  under 
the  influence  of  more  or  less  clearly  conscious  philosophical  motives. 
He  does  not  usually  attempt  to  define  what  distinguishes  a  signi- 
ficant from  a  trivial  system  of  postulates,  or  what  constitutes  a  pro- 
blem worth  attacking  from  the  point  of  view  of  pure  mathematics. 
But  he  practically  recognizes  such  a  distinction  between  the  trivial 
and  the  significant  regions  of  the  world  of  ideal  truth,  and  since 
philosophy  is  concerned  with  the  significance  of  ideas,  this  recogni- 
tion brings  the  mathematician  near  in  spirit  to  the  philosopher. 

Such,  then,  is  the  position  of  the  pure  mathematician.    What,  by 
way  of  contrast,  is  that  of  the  philosopher?    We  may  reply  that  to 
state  the  formal  consequences  of  exact  assumptions  is  one  thing;  to 
reflect  upon  the  mutual  relations,  and  the  whole  significance  of  such 
assumptions,  does  indeed  involve  other  interests;    and  these  other 
interests  are  the  ones  which  directly  carry  us  over  to  the  realm  of 
philosophy.    If  the  theory  of  numbers  belongs  to  pure  mathematics, 
the  study  of  the  place  of  the  number  concept  in  the  system  of 
human  ideas  belongs  to  philosophy.     Like  the  mathematician,  the 
philosopher  deals  directly  with  a  realm  of  ideal  truth.    But  to  unify 
our  knowledge,  to  comprehend  its  sources,  its  meaning,  and  its  re- 
lations to  the  whole  of  human  life,  these  aims  constitute  the  proper 
goal  of  the  philosopher.    In  order,  however,  to  accomplish  his  aims, 
the  philosopher  must,  indeed,  take  account  of  the  results  of  the 
special  physical  science;    but  he  must  also  turn  from  the  world  of 
outer  phenomena  to  an  ideal  world.   For  the  unity  of  things  is  never, 
for  us  mortals,,  any  thing  that  we  find  given  in  our  experience.    You 
cannot  see  the  unity  of  knowledge;  you  cannot  describe  it  as  a  phe- 
nomenon.  It  is  for  us  now,  an  ideal.    And  precisely  so,  the  mean- 
ing of  things,  the  relation  of  knowledge  to  life,  the  significance  of 
our  ideals,  their  bearing  upon  one  another  —  these  are  never,  for  us 
men,  phenomenally  present  data.    Hence  the  philosopher,  however 
much  he  ought,  as  indeed  he  ought,  to  take  account  of  phenomena, 
and  of  the  results  of  the  special  physical  sciences,  is  quite  as  deeply 
interested  in  his  own  way,  as  the  mathematician  is  interested  in  his 


156  NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 

way,  in  the  consideration  of  an  ideal  realm.  Only,  unlike  the  mathe- 
matician, the  philosopher  does  not  first  abstract  from  the  empirical 
suggestions  upon  which  his  exact  ideas  are  actually  based,  and  then 
content  himself  merely  with  developing  the  logical  consequences  of 
these  ideas.  On  the  contrary,  his  main  interest  is  not  in  any  idea  or 
fact  in  so  far  as  it  is  viewed  by  itself,  but  rather  in  the  interrelations, 
in  the  common  significance,  in  the  unity,  of  all  fundamental  ideas, 
and  in  their  relations  both  to  the  phenomenal  facts  and  to  life!  On 
the  whole,  he,  therefore,  neither  consents,  like  the  student  of  a  special 
science  of  experience,  to  seek  his  freedom  solely  through  conformity 
to  the  phenomena  which  are  to  be  described;  nor  is  he  content,  like 
the  pure  mathematician,  to  win  his  truth  solely  through  the  exact 
definition  of  the  formal  consequences  of  his  freely  defined  hypotheses. 
He  is  making  an  effort  to  discover  the  sense  and  the  unity  of  the 
business  of  his  own  life. 

It  is  no  part  of  my  purpose  to  attempt  to  show  here  how  this  gen- 
eral philosophical  interest  differentiates  into  the  various  interests  of 
metaphysics,  of  the  philosophy  of  religion,  of  ethics,  of  aesthetics, 
of  logic.  Enough  —  I  have  tried  to  illustrate  how,  while  both  the 
philosopher  and  the  mathematician  have  an  interest  in  the  meaning 
of  ideas  rather  than  in  the  description  of  external  facts,  still  there 
is  a  contrast  which  does,  indeed,  keep  their  work  in  large  measure 
asunder,  namely,  the  contrast  due  to  the  fact  that  the  mathematician 
is  directly  concerned  with  developing  the  consequences  of  certain 
freely  assumed  systems  of  postulates  or  hypotheses;  while  the  philo- 
sopher is  interested  in  the  significance,  in  the  unity,  and  in  the  re- 
lation to  life,  of  all  the  fundamental  ideals  and  postulates  of  the 
human  mind. 

Yet  not  even  thus  do  we  sufficiently  state  how  closely  related 
the  two  tasks  are.  For  this  very  contrast,  as  we  have  also  suggested, 
is,  even  within  its  own  limits,  no  final  or  perfectly  sharp  contrast. 
There  is  a  deep  analogy  between  the  two  tasks.  For  the  mathema- 
tician, as  we  have  just  seen,  is  not  evenly  interested  in  developing 
the  consequences  of  any  and  every  system  of  freely  assumed  pos- 
tulates. He  is  no  mere  solver  of  arbitrary  ideal  puzzles  in  general. 
His  systems  of  postulates  are  so  chosen  as  to  be  not  trivial,  but  sig- 
nificant. They  are,  therefore,  in  fact,  but  abstractly  defined  aspects 
of  the  very  system  of  eternal  truth  whose  expression  is  the  universe. 
In  this  sense  the  mathematician  is  as  genuinely  interested  as  is  the 
philosopher  in  the  significant  use  of  his  scientific  freedom.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  philosopher,  in  reflecting  upon  the  significance  and 
the  unity  of  fundamental  ideas,  can  only  do  so  with  success  in  case 
he  makes  due  inquiry  into  the  logical  consequences  of  given  ideas. 
And  this  he  can  accomplish  only  if,  upon  occasion,  he  employs  the 
exact  methods  of  the  mathematician,  and  develops  his  sj^stems  of 


THE  SCIENCES  OF  THE  IDEAL  157 

ideal  truth  with  the  precision  of  which  only  mathematical  research 
is  capable.  As  a  fact,  then,  the  mathematician  and  the  philosopher 
deal  with  ideal  truth  in  ways  which  are  not  only  contrasted,  but 
profoundly  interconnected.  The  mathematician,  in  so  far  as  he  con- 
sciously distinguishes  significant  from  trivial  problems,  and  ideal 
systems,  is  a  philosopher.  The  philosopher,  in  so  far  as  he  seeks 
exactness  of  logical  method,  in  his  reflection,  must  meanwhile  aim 
to  be,  within  his  own  limits,  a  mathematician.  He,  indeed,  will  not 
in  future,  like  Spinoza,  seek  to  reduce  philosophy  to  the  mere  develop- 
ment, in  mathematical  form,  of  the  consequences  of  certain  arbitrary 
hypotheses.  He  will  distinguish  between  a  reflection  upon  the  unity 
of  the  system  of  truth  and  an  abstract  development  of  this  or  that 
selected  aspect  of  the  system.  But  he  will  see  more  and  more  that, 
in  so  far  as  he  undertakes  to  be  exact,  he  must  aim  to  become,  in 
his  own  way,  and  with  due  regard  to  his  own  purposes,  mathemat- 
ical; and  thus  the  union  of  mathematical  and  philosophical  inquiries, 
in  the  future,  will  tend  to  become  closer  and  closer. 

II 

So  far,  then,  I  have  dwelt  upon  extremely  general  considerations 
relating  to  the  unity  and  the  contrast  of  mathematical  and  philo- 
sophical inquiries.  I  can  well  conceive,  however,  that  the  individual 
worker  in  any  one  of  the  numerous  branches  of  investigation  which 
are  represented  by  the  body  of  students  whom  I  am  privileged  to 
address,  may  at  this  point  mentally  interpose  the  objection  that  all 
these  considerations  are",  indeed,  far  too  general  to  be  of  practical 
interest  to  any  of  us.  Of  course,  all  we  who  study  these  so-called 
normative  sciences  are,  indeed,  interested  in  ideas,  for  their  own 
sakes  —  in  ideas  so  distinct  from,  although  of  course  also  somehow 
related  to,  phenomena.  Of  course,  some  of  us  are  rather  devoted  to 
the  development  of  the  consequences  of  exactly  stated  ideal  hypo- 
theses, and  others  to  reflecting  as  we  can  upon  what  certain  ideas  and 
ideals  are  good  for,  and  upon  what  the  unity  is  of  all  ideas  and  ideals. 
Of  course,  if  we  are  wise  enough  to  do  so,  we  have  much  to  learn 
from  one  another.  But,  you  will  say,  the  assertion  of  all  these  things 
is  a  commonplace.  The  expression  of  the  desire  for  further  mutual 
cooperation  is  a  pious  wish.  You  will  insist  upon  asking  further: 
"  Is  there  just  now  any  concrete  instance  in  a  modern  type  of  research 
which  furnishes  results  such  as  are  of  interest  to  all  of  us?  Are 
we  actually  doing  any  productive  work  in  common?  Are  the  philo- 
sophers contributing  anything  to  human  knowledge  which  has  a 
genuine  bearing  upon  the  interests  of  mathematical  science?  Are 
the  mathematicians  contributing  anything  to  philosophy?" 

These  questions  are  perfectly  fair.    Moreover,  as  it  happens,  they 


158  NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 

can  be  distinctly  answered  in  the  affirmative.  The  present  age  is  one 
of  a  rapid  advance  in  the  actual  unification  of  the  fields  of  investi- 
gation which  are  included  within  the  scope  of  this  present  division. 
What  little  time  remains  to  me  must  be  devoted  to  indicating,  as 
well  as  I  can,  in  what  sense  this  is  true.  I  shall  have  still  to  deal 
in  very  broad  generalities.  I  shall  try  to  make  these  generalities 
definite  enough  to  be  not  wholly  unfruitful. 

We  have  already  emphasized  one  question  which  may  be  said  to 
interest,  in  a  very  direct  way,  both  the  mathematician  and  the 
philosopher.  The  ideal  postulates,  whose  consequences  mathemat- 
ical science  undertakes  to  develop,  must  be,  we  have  said,  significant 
postulates,  involving  ideas  whose  exact  definition  and  exposition 
repay  the  labor  of  scientific  scrutiny.  Number,  space,  continuity, 
functional  correspondence  or  dependence,  group-structure  —  these 
are  examples  of  such  significant  ideas;  the  postulates  or  ideal 
assumptions  upon  which  the  theory  of  such  ideas  depends  are  signi- 
ficant postulates,  and  are  not  the  mere  conventions  of  an  arbitrary 
game.  But  now  what  constitutes  the  significance  of  an  idea,  or 
of  an  abstract  mathematical  theory?  What  gives  an  idea  a  worthy 
place  in  the  whole  scheme  of  human  ideas?  Is  it  the  possibility  of 
finding  a  physical  application  for  a  mathematical  theory  which 
for  us  decides  what  is  the  value  of  the  theory?  No,  the  theory  of 
functions,  the  theory  of  numbers,  group  theory,  have  a  significance 
which  no  mathematician  would  consent  to  measure  in  terms  of  the 
present  applicability  or  non-applicability  of  these  theories  in  physical 
science?  In  vain,  then,  does  one  attempt  to  use  the  test  of  applied 
mathematics  as  the  main  criticism  of  the  value  of  a  theory  of  pure 
mathematics.  The  value  of  an  idea,  for  the  sciences  which  con- 
stitute our  division,  is  dependent  upon  the  place  which  this  idea 
occupies  in  the  whole  organized  scheme  or  system  of  human  ideas. 
The  idea  of  number,  for  instance,  familiar  as  its  applications  are, 
does  not  derive  its  main  value  from  the  fact  that  eggs  and  dollars 
and  star-clusters  can  be  counted,  but  rather  from  the  fact  that  the 
idea  of  numbers  has  those  relations  to  other  fundamental  ideas 
which  recent  logical  theory  has  made  prominent  —  relations,  for 
instance,  to  the  concept  of  order,  to  the  theory  of  classes  or  collec- 
tions of  objects  viewed  in  general,  and  to  the  metaphysical  concept 
of  the  self.  Relations  of  this  sort,  which  the  discussions  of  the  num- 
ber concept  by  Dedekind,  Cantor,  Peano,  and  Russell  have  recently 
brought  to  light  —  such  relations,  I  say,  constitute  what  truly  justi- 
fied Gauss  in  calling  the  theory  of  numbers  a  "  divine  science."  As 
against  such  deeper  relations,  the  countless  applications  of  the 
number  concept  in  ordinary  life,  and  in  science,  are,  from  the  truly 
philosophical  point  of  view,  of  comparatively  small  moment.  What 
we  want,  in  the  work  of  our  division  of  the  sciences,  is  to  bring  to 


THE  SCIENCES   OF  THE  IDEAL  159 

light  the  unity  of  truth,  either,  as  in  mathematics,  by  developing 
systems  of  truth  which  are  significant  by  virtue  of  their  actual  rela- 
tions to  this  unity,  or,  as  in  philosophy,  by  explicitly  seeking  the 
central  idea  about  which  all  the  many  ideas  cluster. 

Now,  an  ancient  and  fundamental  problem  for  the  philosophers 
is  that  which  has  been  called  the  problem  of  the  categories.  This 
problem  of  the  categories  is  simply  the  more  formal  aspect  of  the 
whole  philosophical  problem  just  defined.  The  philosopher  aims  to 
comprehend  the  unity  of  the  system  of  human  ideas  and  ideals.  Well, 
then,  what  are  the  primal  ideas?  Upon  what  group  of  concepts  do 
the  other  concepts  of  human  science  logicall}''  depend?  About  what 
central  interests  is  the  system  of  human  ideals  clustered?  In  ancient 
thought  Aristotle  already  approached  this  problem  in  one  way. 
Kant,  in  the  eighteenth  century,  dealt  with  it  in  another.  We  stu- 
dents of  philosophy  are  accustomed  to  regret  what  we  call  the  ex- 
cessive formalism  of  Kant,  to  lament  that  Kant  was  so  much  the 
slave  of  his  own  relatively  superficial  and  accidental  table  of  catego- 
ries, and  that  he  made  the  treatment  of  every  sort  of  philosophical 
problem  turn  upon  his  own  schematism.  Yet  we  cannot  doubt  that 
Kant  was  right  in  maintaining  that  philosophy  needs,  for  the  suc- 
cessful development  of  every  one  of  its  departments,  a  well-devised 
and  substantially  complete  system  of  categories.  Our  objection  to 
Kant's  over-confidence  in  the  virtues  of  his  own  schematism  is  due 
to  the  fact  that  we  do  not  now  accept  his  table  of  categories  as  an 
adequate  view  of  the  fundamental  concepts.  The  efforts  of  philo- 
sophers since  Kant  have  been  repeatedly  devoted  to  the  task  of 
replacing  his  scheme  of  categories  by  a  more  adequate  one.  I  am 
far  from  regarding  these  purely  philosophical  efforts  made  since 
Kant  as  fruitless,  but  they  have  remained,  so  far,  very  incomplete, 
and  they  have  been  held  back  from  their  due  fullness  of  success  by 
the  lack  of  a  sufficiently  careful  survey  and  analysis  of  the  processes 
of  thought  as  these  have  come  to  be  embodied  in  the  living  sciences. 
Such  concepts  as  number,  quantity,  space,  time,  cause,  continuity, 
have  been  dealt  with  by  the  pure  philosophers  far  too  summarily 
and  superficially.  A  more  thoroughgoing  analysis  has  been  needed. 
But  now,  in  comparatively  recent  times,  there  has  developed  a  re- 
gion of  inquiry  which  one  may  call  by  the  general  name  of  modern 
logic.  To  the  constitution  of  this  new  region  of  inquiry  men  have 
principally  contributed  who  began  as  mathematicians,  but  who,  in 
the  course  of  their  work,  have  been  led  to  become  more  and  more 
philosophers.  Of  late,  however,  various  philosophers,  who  were 
originally  in  no  sense  mathematicians,  becoming  aware  of  the  im- 
portance of  the  new  type  of  research,  are  in  their  turn  attempting 
both  to  assimilate  and  to  supplement  the  undertakings  which  were 
begun  from  the  mathematical  side.   As  a  result,  the  logical  problem 


160  NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 

of  the  categories  has  to-day  become  almost  equally  a  problem  for 
the  logicians  of  mathematics  and  for  those  students  of  philosophy 
who  take  any  serious  interest  in  exactness  of  method  in  their  own 
branch  of  work.  The  result  of  this  actual  cooperation  of  men  from 
both  sides  is  that,  as  I  think,  we  are  to-day,  for  the  first  time,  in 
sight  of  what  is  still,  as  I  freely  admit,  a  somewhat  distant  goal, 
namely,  the  relatively  complete  rational  analysis  and  tabulation  of 
the  fundamental  categories  of  human  thought.  That  the  student  of 
ethics  is  as  much  interested  in  such  an  investigation  as  is  the  meta- 
physician, that  the  philosopher  of  religion  needs  a  well-completed 
table  of  categories  quite  as  much  as  does  the  pure  logician,  every 
competent  student  of  such  topics  ought  to  admit.  And  that  the 
enterprise  in  question  keenly  interests  the  mathematicians  is  shown 
by  the  prominent  part  which  some  of  them  have  taken  in  the  re- 
searches in  question.  Here,  then,  is  the  type  of  recent  scientific  work 
whose  results  most  obviously  bear  upon  the  tasks  of  all  of  us  alike. 
A  catalogue  of  the  names  of  the  workers  in  this  wide  field  of 
modern  logic  would  be  out  of  place  here.  Yet  one  must,  indeed, 
indicate  what  lines  of  research  are  especially  in  question.  From  the 
purelj'"  mathematical  side,  the  investigations  of  the  type  to  which  I 
now  refer  may  be  viewed  (somewhat  arbitrarily)  as  beginning  with 
that  famous  examination  into  one  of  the  postulates  of  Euclid's 
geometry  which  gave  rise  to  the  so-called  non-Euclidean  geometry. 
The  question  here  originally  at  issue  was  one  of  a  comparatively 
limited  scope,  namely,  the  question  whether  Euclid's  parallel-line 
postulate  was  a  logical  consequence  of  the  other  geometrical  prin- 
ciples. But  the  investigation  rapidly  develops  into  a  general  study 
of  the  foundations  of  geometry  —  a  study  to  which  contributions 
are  still  almost  constantly  appearing.  Somewhat  independently 
of  this  line  of  inquiry  there  grew  up,  during  the  latter  half  of  the 
nineteenth  century,  that  reexamination  of  the  bases  of  arithmetic 
and  analysis  which  is  associated  with  the  names  of  Dedekind,  Weier- 
strass,  and  George  Cantor.  At  the  present  time,  the  labors  of  a  num- 
ber of  other  inquirers  (amongst  whom  we  may  mention  the  school 
of  Peano  and  Fieri  in  Italy,  and  men  such  as  Poincare  and  Couturat 
in  France,  Hilbert  in  Germany,  Bertrand  Russell  and  Whitehead  in 
England,  and  an  energetic  group  of  our  American  mathematicians 
—  men  such  as  Professor  Moore,  Professor  Halsted,  Dr.  Hunting- 
ton, Dr.  Veblen,  and  a  considerable  number  of  others)  have  been 
added  to  the  earlier  researches.  The  result  is  that  we  have  recently 
come  for  the  first  time  to  be  able  to  see,  with  some  completeness, 
what  the  assumed  first  principles  of  pure  mathematics  actually  are. 
As  was  to  be  expected,  these  principles  are  capable  of  more  than 
one  formulation,  according  as  they  are  approached  from  one  side  or 
from  another.    As  was  also  to  be  expected,  the  entire  edifice  of  pure 


THE   SCIENCES  OF  THE  IDEAL       •  161 

mathematics,  so  far  as  it  has  yet  been  erected,  actually  rests  upon 
a  very  few  fundamental  concepts  and  postulates,  however  you  may 
formulate  them.  What  was  not  observed,  however,  by  the  earlier, 
and  especially  by  the  philosophical,  students  of  the  categories,  is 
the  form  which  these  postulates  tend  to  assume  when  they  are 
rigidly  analyzed. 

This  form  depends  upon  the  precise  definition  and  classification 
of  certain  types  of  relations.  The  whole  of  geometry,  for  instance, 
including  metrical  geometry,  can  be  developed  from  a  set  of  postu- 
lates which  demand  the  existence  of  points  that  stand  in  certain 
ordinal  relationships.  The  ordinal  relationships  can  be  reduced, 
according  as  the  series  of  points  considered  is  open  or  closed,  either 
to  the  well-known  relationship  in  which  three  points  stand  when 
one  is  between  the  other  two  upon  a  right  line,  or  else  to  the  ordinal 
relationship  in  which  four  points  stand  when  they  are  separated  by 
pairs;  and  these  two  ordinal  relationships,  by  means  of  various  log- 
ical devices,  can  be  regarded  as  variations  of  a  single  fundamental 
form.  Cayley  and  Klein  founded  the  logical  theory  of  geometry  here 
in  question.  Russell,  and  in  another  way  Dr.  Veblen,  have  given 
it  its  most  recent  expressions.  In  the  same  way,  the  theory  of  whole 
numbers  can  be  redut^ed  to  sets  of  principles  which  demand  the  exist- 
ence of  certain  ideal  objects  in  certain  simple  ordinal  relations.  Dede- 
kind  and  Peano  have  worked  out  such  ordinal  theories  of  the  num- 
ber concept.  In  another  development  of  the  theory  of  the  cardinal 
whole  numbers,  which  Russell  and  Whitehead  have  worked  out, 
ordinal  concepts  are  introduced  only  secondarily,  and  the  theory 
depends  upon  the  fundamental  relation  of  the  equivalence  or  non- 
equivalence  of  collections  of  objects.  But  here  also  a  certain  simple 
type  of  relation  determines  the  definitions  and  the  development  of 
the  whole  theory. 

Two  results  follow  from  such  a  fashion  of  logically  analyzing  the 
first  principles  of  mathematical  science.  In  the  first  place,  as  just 
pointed  out,  we  learn  how  jew  and  simple  are  the  conceptions  and  pos- 
tulates upon  which  the  actual  edifice  of  exact  science  rests.  Pure 
mathematics,  we  have  said,  is  free  to  assume  what  it  chooses.  Yet 
the  assumptions  whose  presence  as  the  foundation  principles  of  the 
actually  existent  pure  mathematics  an  exhaustive  examination  thus 
reveals,  show  by  their  fe^^^less  that  the  ideal  freedom  of  the  mathe- 
matician to  assume  and  to  construct  what  he  pleases,  is  indeed,  in 
practice,  a  very  decidedly  limited  freedom.  The  limitation  is,  as  we 
have  already  seen,  a  limitation  which  has  to  do  with  the  essential 
significance  of  the  fundamental  concepts  in  question.  And  so  the 
result  of  this  analysis  of  the  bases  of  the  actually  developed  and 
significant  branches  of  mathematics,  constitutes  a  sort  of  empirical 
revelation  of  what  categories  the  exact  sciences  have  practically 


162  NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 

found  to  be  of  such  significance  as  to  be  worthy  of  exhaustive  treat- 
ment. Thus  the  instinctive  sense  for  significant  truth,  which  has  all 
along  been  guiding  the  development  of  mathematics,  comes  at  least 
to  a  clear  and  philosophical  consciousness.  And  meanwhile  the  es- 
sential categories  of  thought  are  seen  in  a  new  light. 

The  second  result  still  more  directly  concerns  a  philosophical  logic. 
It  is  this:  Since  the  few  types  of  relations  which  this  sort  of  ana- 
lysis reveals  as  the  fundamental  ones  in  exact  science  are  of  such 
importance,  the  logic  of  the  present  day  is  especially  required  to  face 
the  questions :  What  is  the  nature  of  our  concept  of  relations  f  What 
are  the  various  possible  types  of  relations?  Upon  what  does  the 
variety  of  these  types  depend?  What  unity  lies  beneath  the  variety? 

As  a  fact,  logic,  in  its  modern  forms,  namely,  first  that  symbolic 
logic  which  Boole  first  formulated,  which  Mr.  Charles  S.  Peirce  and 
his  pupils  have  in  this  country  already  so  highly  developed,  and 
which  Schroeder  in  Germany,  Peano's  school  in  Italy,  and  a  num- 
ber of  recent  English  writers  have  so  effectively  furthered  —  and 
secondly,  the  logic  of  scientific  method,  which  is  now  so  actively 
pursued,  in  France,  in  Germany,  and  in  the  English-speaking  coun- 
tries —  this  whole  movement  in  modern  logic,  as  I  hold,  is  rapidly 
approaching  new  solutions  of  the  problem  of  the  fundamental  nature 
and  the  logic  of  relations.  The  problem  is  one  in  which  we  are  all 
equally  interested.  To  De  Morgan  in  England,  in  an  earlier  genera- 
tion, and,  in  our  time,  to  Charles  Peirce  in  this  country,  very  im- 
portant stages  in  the  growth  of  these  problems  are  due.  Russell,  in 
his  work  on  the  Principles  of  Mathematics  has  very  lately  under- 
taken to  sum  up  the  results  of  the  logic  of  relations,  as  thus  far 
developed,  and  to  add  his  own  interpretations.  Yet  I  think  that 
Russell  has  failed  to  get  as  near  to  the  foundations  of  the  theory 
of  relations  as  the  present  state  of  the  discussion  permits.  For 
Russell  has  failed  to  take  account  of  what  I  hold  to  be  the  most 
fundamentally  important  generalization  yet  reached  in  the  general 
theory  of  relations.  This  is  the  generalization  set  forth  as  early  as 
1890,  by  Mr.  A.  B.  Kempe,  of  London,  in  a  pair  of  wonderful  but 
too  much  neglected,  papers,  entitled,  respectively.  The  Theory  of 
Mathematical  Form,  and  The  Analogy  between  the  Logical  Theory 
of  Classes  and  the  Geometrical  Theory  of  Points.  A  mere  hint  first 
as  to  the  more  precise  formulation  of  the  problem  at  issue,  and  then 
later  as  to  Kempe 's  special  contribution  to  that  problem,  may  be  in 
order  here,  despite  the  impossibility  of  any  adequate  statement. 

Ill 

The  two  most  obviously  and  universally  important  kinds  of  rela- 
tions known  to  the  exact  sciences,  as  these  sciences  at  present  exist, 
are:  (1)  The  relations  of  the  type  of  equality  or  equivalence;    and 


THE  SCIENCES   OF   THE  IDEAL  163 

(2)  the  relations  of  the  type  of  before  and  after,  or  greater  and  less. 
The  first  of  these  two  classes  of  relations,  namely,  the  class  repre- 
sented, although  by  no  means  exhausted,  by  the  various  relations 
actually  called,  in  different  branches  of  science  by  the  one  name 
equality,  this  class  I  say,  might  well  be  named,  as  I  myself  have 
proposed,  the  leveling  relations.  A  collection  of  objects  between 
any  two  of  which  some  one  relation  of  this  type  holds,  may  be  said 
to  be  a  collection  whose  members,  in  some  defined  sense  or  other, 
are  on  the  same  level.  The  second  of  these  two  classes  of  relations, 
namely,  those  of  the  type  of  before  and  after,  or  greater  and  less 
■ —  this  class  of  relations,  I  say,  consists  of  what  are  nowadays  often 
called  the  serial  relations.  And  a  collection  of  objects  such  that,  if 
any  pair  of  these  objects  be  chosen,  a  determinate  one  of  this  pair 
stands  to  the  other  one  of  the  same  pair  in  some  determinate  rela- 
tion of  this  second  type,  and  in  a  relation  which  remains  constant 
for  all  the  pairs  that  can  be  thus  formed  out  of  the  members  of  this 
collection  —  any  such  collection,  I  say,  constitutes  a  one-dimen- 
sional open  series.  Thus,  in  case  of  a  file  of  men,  if  you  choose  any 
pair  of  men  belonging  to  the  file,  a  determinate  one  of  them  is,  in  the 
file,  before  the  other.  In  the  number  series,  of  any  two  numbers, 
a  determinate  one  is  greater  than  the  other.  Wherever  such  a  state 
of  affairs  exists,  one  has  a  series. 

Now  these  two  classes  of  relations,  the  leveling  relations  and  the 
serial  relations,  agree  with  one  another,  and  differ  from  one  another 
in  very  momentous  ways.  They  agree  with  one  another  in  that  both 
the  leveling  and  the  serial  relations  are  what  is  technically  called 
transitive;  that  is,  both  classes  conform  to  what  Professor  James 
has  caUed  the  law  of  "skipped  intermediaries."  Thus,  if  A  is  equal 
to  B,  and  B  is  equal  to  C,  it  follows  that  A  is  equal  to  C.  If  A  is 
before  B,  and  B  is  before  C,  then  A  is  before  C.  And  this  property, 
which  enables  you  in  your  reasonings  about  these  relations  to  skip 
middle  terms,  and  so  to  perform  some  operation  of  elimination,  is 
the  property  which  is  meant  when  one  calls  relations  of  this  type 
transitive.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  these  two  classes  of  relations 
differ  from  each  other  in  that  the  leveling  relations  are,  while  the 
serial  relations  are  not,  symmetrical  or  reciprocal.  Thus,  if  A  is  equal 
to  B,  B  is  equal  to  A.  But  if  X  is  greater  than  Y,  then  Y  is  not 
greater  than  X,  but  less  than  X.  So  the  leveling  relations  are  sym- 
metrical transitive  relations.  But  the  serial  relations  are  transitive 
relations  which  are  not  symmetrical. 

All  this  is  now  well  known.  It  is  notable,  however,  that  nearly 
all  the  processes  of  our  exact  sciences,  as  at  present  developed, 
can  be  said  to  be  essentially  such  as  lead  either  to  the  placing  of  sets 
or  classes  of  objects  on  the  same  level,  by  means  of  the  use  of  sym- 
metrical transitive  relations,  or  else  to  the  arranging  of  objects  in 


164  NORMATIVE   SCIENCE 

orderly  rows  or  series,  by  means  of  the  use  of  transitive  relations 
which  are  not  symmetrical.  This  holds  also  of  all  the  applications 
of  the  exact  sciences.  Whatever  else  you  do  in  science  (or,  for  that 
matter,  in  art),  you  alwaj^s  lead,  in  the  end,  either  to  the  arrang- 
ing of  objects,  or  of  ideas,  or  of  acts,  or  of  movements,  in  rows  or 
series,  or  else  to  the  placing  of  objects  or  ideas  of  some  sort  on  the 
same  level,  by  virtue  of  some  equivalence,  or  of  some  invariant 
character.  Thus  numbers,  functions,  lines  in  geometry,  give  you 
examples  of  serial  relations.  Equations  in  mathematics  are  classic 
instances  of  leveling  relations.  So,  of  course,  are  invariants.  Thus, 
again,  the  whole  modern  theory  of  energy  consists  of  two  parts, 
one  of  which  has  to  do  with  levels  of  energy,  in  so  far  as  the  quan- 
tity of  energy  of  a  closed  system  remains  invariant  through  all  the 
transformations  of  the  system,  while  the  other  part  has  to  do  with 
the  irreversible  serial  order  of  the  transformations  of  energy  them- 
selves, which  follow  a  set  of  unsymmetrical  relations,  in  so  far  as 
energy  tends  to  fall  from  higher  to  lower  levels  of  intensity  within 
the  same  system. 

The  entire  conceivable  universe  then,  and  all  of  our  present  exact 
science,  can  be  viewed,  if  you  choose,  as  a  collection  of  objects  or 
of  ideas  that,  whatever  other  types  of  relations  may  exist,  are  at 
least  largely  characterized  either  by  the  leveling  relations,  or  by 
the  serial  relations,  or  by  complexes  of  both  sorts  of  relations.  Here, 
then,  we  are  plainly  dealing  with  very  fundamental  categories. 
The  "between"  relations  of  geometry  can  of  course  be  defined,  if 
you  choose,  in  terms  of  transitive  relations  that  are  not  symmet- 
rical. There  are,  to  be  sure,  some  other  relations  present  in  exact 
science,  but  the  two  types,  the  serial  and  leveling  relations,  are 
especially  notable. 

So  far  the  modern  logicians  have  for  some  time  been  in  substan- 
tial agreement.  Russell's  brilliant  book  is  a  development  of  the 
logic  of  mathematics  very  largely  in  terms  of  the  two  types  of  rela- 
tions which,  in  my  own  way,  I  have  just  characterized;  although 
Russell  gives  due  regard,  of  course,  to  certain  other  types  of  rela- 
tions. 

But  hereupon  the  question  arises,  "Are  these  two  types  of  rela- 
tions what  Russell  holds  them  to  be,  namely,  ultimate  and  irre- 
ducible logical  facts,  unanalyzable  categories  —  mere  data  for  the 
thinker?  Or  can  we  reduce  them  still  further,  and  thus  simplify 
yet  again  our  view  of  the  categories? 

Here  is  where  Kempe's  generalization  begins  to  come  into  sight. 
These  two  categories,  in  at  least  one  very  fundamental  realm  of 
exact  thought,  can  be  reduced  to  one.  There  is,  namel}'',  a  world 
of  ideal  objects  which  especially  interest  the  logician.  It  is  the 
world  of  a  totality  of  possible  logical  classes,  or  again,  it  is  the  ideal 


THE  SCIENCES.  OF   THE  IDEAL  165 

world,  equivalent  in  formal  structure  to  the  foregoing,  but  composed 
of  a  totality  of  possible  statements,  or  thirdly,  it  is  the  world,  equiva- 
lent once  more,  in  formal  structure,  to  the  foregoing,  but  consisting 
of  a  totality  of  possible  acts  of  will,  of  possible  decisions.  When  we 
proceed  to  consider  the  relational  structure  of  such  a  world,  taken 
merely  in  the  abstract  as  such  a  structure,  a  relation  comes  into 
sight  which  at  once  appears  to  be  peculiarly  general  in  its  nature. 
It  is  the  so-caUed  illative  relation,  the  relation  which  obtains  between 
two  classes  when  one  is  subsumed  under  tke  other,  or  between  two 
statements,  or  two  decisions,  when  one  implies  or  entails  the  other. 
This  relation  is  transitive,  but  may  be  either  symmetrical  or  not 
symmetrical;  so  that,  according  as  it  is  symmetrical  or  not,  it  may 
be  used  either  to  establish  levels  or  to  generate  series.  In  the  order 
system  of  the  logician's  world,  the  relational  structure  is  thus,  in 
any  case,  a  highly  general  and  fundamental  one. 

But  this  is  not  all.  In  this  the  logician's  world  of  classes,  or  of 
statements,  or  of  decisions,  there  is  also  another  relation  observable. 
This  is  the  relation  of  exclusion  or  mutual  opposition.  This  is  a 
purely  symmetrical  or  reciprocal  relation.  It  has  two  forms  — 
obverse  or  contradictory  opposition,  that  is,  negation  proper,  and 
contrary  opposition.  But  both  these  forms  are  purely  symmetrical. 
And  by  proper  devices  each  of  them  can  be  stated  in  terms  of  the 
other,  or  reduced  to  the  other.  And  further,  as  Kempe  incidentally 
shows,  and  as  Mrs.  Ladd  Franklin  has  also  substantiall}'-  shown  in 
her  important  theory  of  the  syllogism,  it  is  possible  to  state  every 
proposition,  or  complex  of  propositions  involving  the  illative  relation, 
in  terms  of  this  purely  symmetrical  relation  of  opposition.  Hence, 
so  far  as  mere  relational  form  is  concerned,  the  illative  relation  itself 
may  be  wholly  reduced  to  the  symmetrical  relation  of  opposition. 
This  is  our  first  result  as  to  the  relational  structure  of  the  realm  of 
pure  logic,  that  is,  the  realm  of  classes,  of  statements,  or  of  deci- 
sions. 

It  follows  that,  in  describing  the  logician's  world  of  possible  classes 
or  of  possible  decisions,  all  unsymmetrical,  and  so  all  serial,  relations 
can  be  stated  solely  in  terms  of  symmetrical  relations,  and  can  be  entirely 
reduced  to  such  relations.  Moreover,  as  Kempe  has  also  very  prettily 
shown,  the  relation  of  opposition,  in  its  two  forms,  just  mentioned, 
need  not  be  interpreted  as  obtaining  merely  between  pairs  of  objects. 
It  may  and  does  obtain  between  triads,  tetrads,  n-ads  of  logical  en- 
tities; and  so  all  that  is  true  of  the  relations  of  logical  classes  may 
consequently  be  stated  merely  by  ascribing  certain  perfectly  sym- 
metrical and  homogeneous  predicates  to  pairs,  triads,  tetrads,  n-ads 
of  logical  objects.  The  essential  contrast  between  symmetrical 
and  unsymmetrical  relations  thus,  in  this  ideal  realm  of  the  logi- 
cian, simply  vanishes.     The  categories  of  the  logician's  world  of 


166  NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 

classes,  of  statements,  or  of  decisions,  are  marvelously  simple.  All 
the  relations  present  may  be  viewed  as  variations  of  the  mere  con- 
ception of  opposition  as  distinct  from  non-opposition. 

All  this  holds,  of  course,  so  far,  merely  for  the  logician's  world  of 
classes  or  of  decisions.  There,  at  least,  all  serial  order  can  actually 
be  derived  from  wholly  symmetrical  relations.  But  Kempe  now 
very  beautifully  shows  (and  here  lies  his  great  and  original  contri- 
bution to  our  topic)  —  he  shows,  I  say,  that  the  ordinal  relations 
of  geometry,  as  well  as  of  the  number-system,  can  all  be  regarded 
as  indistinguishable  from  mere  variations  of  those  relations  which, 
in  pure  logic,  one  finds  to  he  the  symmetrical  relations  obtaining  within 
pairs  or  triads  of  classes  or  of  statements.  The  formal  identity  of  the 
geometrical  relation  called  "between"  with  a  purely  logical  relation 
which  one  can  define  as  existing  or  as  not  existing  amongst  the  mem- 
bers of  a  given  triad  of  logical  classes,  or  of  logical  statements,  is 
shown  by  Kempe  in  a  fashion  that  I  cannot  here  attempt  to  expound. 
But  Kempe's  result  thus  enables  one,  as  I  believe,  to  simplify  the 
theory  of  relations  far  beyond  the  point  which  Russell  in  his  brilliant 
book  has  reached.  For  Kempe's  triadic  relation  in  question  can  be 
stated,  in  what  he  calls  its  obverse  form,  in  perfectly  symmetrical 
terms.  And  he  proves  very  exactly  that  the  resulting  logical  rela- 
tion is  precisely  identical,  in  all  its  properties,  with  the  fundamental 
ordinal  relation  of  geometry. 

Thus  the  order-systems  of  geometry  and  analysis  appear  simply 
as  special  cases  of  the  more  general  order-system  of  pure  logic.  The 
whole,  both  of  analysis  and  of  geometrj^,  can  be  regarded  as  a  de- 
scription of  certain  selected  groups  of  entities,  which  are  chosen, 
according  to  special  rules,  from  a  single  ideal  world.  This  general 
and  inclusive  ideal  world  consists  simply  of  all  the  objects  which  can 
stand  to  one  another  in  those  symmetrical  relations  wherein  the  pure  lo- 
gician finds  various  statements,  or  various  decisions  inevitably  standing. 
''  Let  me,"  says  in  substance  Kempe,  "  choose  from  the  logician's 
ideal  world  of  classes  or  decisions,  what  entities  I  will;  and  I  will 
show  you  a  collection  of  objects  that  are  in  their  relational  structure, 
precisely  identical  with  the  points  of  a  geometer's  space  of  n  dimen- 
sions." In  other  words,  all  of  the  geometer's  figures  and  relations  can 
be  precisely  pictured  by  the  relational  structure  of  a  selected  system 
of  classes  or  of  statements,  whose  relations  are  wholly  and  explicitly 
logical  relations,  such  as  opposition,  and  whose  relations  may  all 
be  regarded,  accordingly,  as  reducible  to  a  single  type  of  purely 
symmetrical  relation. 

Thus,  for  all  exact  science,  and  not  merely  for  the  logician's  special 
realm,  the  contrast  between  symmetrical  and  unsymmetrical  rela- 
tions proves  to  be,  after  all,  superficial  and  derived.  The  purely 
logical  categories,  such  as  opposition,  and  such  as  hold  within  the 


THE  SCIENCES   OF   THE  IDEAL  167 

calculus  of  statements,  are,  apparently,  the  basal  categories  of  all 
the  exact  science  that  has  yet  been  developed.  Series  and  levels  are 
relational  structures  that,  sharply  as  they  are  contrasted,  can  be 
derived  from  a  single  root. 

I  have  restated  Kempe's  generalization  in  my  own  way.  I  think 
it  the  most  promising  step  towards  new  light  as  to  the  categories 
that  we  have  made  for  some  generations. 

In  the  field  of  modern  logic,  I  say,  then,  work  is  doing  which  is 
rapidly  tending  towards  the  unification  of  the  tasks  of  our  entire 
division.  For  this  problem  of  the  categories,  in  all  its  abstractness, 
is  still  a  common  problem  for  all  of  us.  Do  you  ask,  however,  what 
such  researches  can  do  to  furnish  more  special  aid  to  the  workers 
in  metaphysics,  in  the  philosophy  of  religion,  in  ethics,  or  in  aesthetics, 
beyond  merely  helping  towards  the  formulation  of  a  table  of  cate- 
gories —  then  I  reply  that  we  are  already  not  without  evidence  that 
such  general  researches,  abstract  though  they  may  seem,  are  bear- 
ing fruits  which  have  much  more  than  a  merely  special  interest. 
Apart  from  its  most  general  problems,  that  analysis  of  mathemat- 
ical concepts  to  which  I  have  referred  has  in  any  case  revealed 
numerous  unexpected  connections  between  departments  of  thought 
which  had  seemed  to  be  very  widely  sundered.  One  instance  of  such 
a  connection  I  myself  have  elsewhere  discussed  at  length,  in  its  gen- 
eral metaphysical  bearings.  I  refer  to  the  logical  identity  which 
Dedekind  first  pointed  out  between  the  mathematical  concept  of 
the  ordinal  number  of  series  and  the  philosophical  concept  of  the 
formal  structure  of  an  ideally  completed  self.  I  have  maintained 
that  this  formal  identity  throws  light  upon  problems  which  have  as 
genuine  an  interest  for  the  student  of  the  philosophy  of  religion  as 
for  the  logician  of  arithmetic.  In  the  same  connection  it  may  be 
remarked  that,  as  Couturat  and  Russell,  amongst  other  writers, 
have  very  clearly  and  beautifully  shown,  the  argument  of  the  Kant- 
ian mathematical  antinomies  needs  to  be  explicitly  and  totally 
revised  in  the  light  of  Cantor's  modern  theory  of  infinite  collections. 
To  pass  at  once  to  another,  and  a  very  different  instance :  The  mod- 
ern mathematical  conceptions  of  what  is  called  group  theory  have 
already  received  very  wide  and  significant  applications,  and  promise 
to  bring  into  unity  regions  of  research  which,  until  recently,  appeared 
to  have  little  or  nothing  to  do  with  one  another.  Quite  lately,  how- 
ever, there  are  signs  that  group  theory  will  soon  prove  to  be  of  im- 
portance for  the  definition  of  some  of  the  fundamental  concepts  of 
that  most  refractory  branch  of  philosophical  inquiry,  aesthetics.  Dr. 
Emch,  in  an  important  paper  in  the  Monist,  called  attention,  some 
time  since,  to  the  symmetry  groups  to  which  certain  aesthetically 
pleasing  forms  belong,  and  endeavored  to  point  out  the  empirical 
relations  between  these  groups  and  the  aesthetic  effects  in  question . 


168  NORMATIVE  SCIENCE 

The  grounds  for  such  a  connection  between  the  groups  in  question 
and  the  observed  sesthetic  effects,  seemed,  in  the  paper  of  Dr.  Emch 
to  be  left  largely  in  the  dark.  But  certain  papers  recently  published 
in  the  country  by  Miss  Ethel  Puffer,  bearing  upon  the  psychology 
of  the  beautiful  (although  the  author  has  approached  the  subject 
without  being  in  the  least  consciously  influenced,  as  I  understand, 
by  the  conceptions  of  the  mathematical  group  theory),  still  actually 
lead,  if  I  correctly  grasp  the  writer's  meaning,  to  the  doctrine  that 
the  sesthetic  object,  viewed  as  a  psychological  whole,  must  possess 
a  structure  closely,  if  not  precisely,  equivalent  to  the  ideal  structure 
of  what  the  mathematician  calls  a  group.  I  myself  have  no  authority 
regarding  sesthetic  concepts,  and  speak  subject  to  correction.  But 
the  unexpected,  and  in  case  of  Miss  Puffer's  research,  quite  unin- 
tended, appearance  of  group  theory  in  recent  sesthetic  analysis  is  to 
me  an  impressive  instance  of  the  use  of  relatively  new  mathematical 
conceptions  in  philosophical  regions  which  seem,  at  first  sight,  very 
remote  from  mathematics. 

That  both  the  group  concept  and  the  concept  of  the  self  just  sug- 
gested are  sure  to  have  also  a  wide  application  in  the  ethics  of  the 
future,  I  am  myself  well  convinced.  In  fact,  no  branch  of  philosophy  is 
without  close  relations  to  all  such  studies  of  fundamental  categories. 

These  are  but  hints  and  examples.  They  suffice,  I  hope,  to  show 
that  the  workers  in  this  division  have  deep  common  interests,  and 
will  do  well,  in  future,  to  study  the  arts  of  cooperation,  and  to  regard 
one  another's  progress  with  a  watchful  and  cordial  sympathy.  In  a 
word:  Our  common  problem  is  the  theory  of  the  categories.  That 
problem  can  be  solved  only  by  the  cooperation  of  the  mathema- 
ticians and  of  the  philosophers. 


DEPARTMENT   I  —  PHILOSOPHY 


DEPARTMENT  I  —  PHILOSOPHY 

{Hall  6,  September  20,  11.15  a.  m.) 


CHAiRiLVN:  Professor  Borden  P.  Bowne,  Boston  University. 
Speakers:   Professor  George  H.  Howison,  University  of  California. 
Professor  George  T.  Ladd,  Yale  University. 


In  opening  the  Department  of  Philosophy,  the  Chairman,  Pro- 
fessor Borden  P.  Bowne,  LL.D.,  of  Boston  University,  made  an 
interesting  address  on  the  Philosophical  Outlook.  Professor  Bowne 
said  in  part :  — 

I  congratulate  the  members  of  the  Philosophical  Section  on  the  improved  out- 
look in  philosophy.  In  the  generation  just  passed,  philosophy  was  somewhat  at 
a  discount.  The  great  and  rapid  development  of  physical  science  and  invention, 
together  with  the  profound  changes  in  biological  thought,  produced  for  a  time  a 
kind  of  chaos.  New  facts  were  showered  upon  us  in  great  abundance,  and  we  had 
no  adequate  philosophical  preparation  for  dealing  with  them.  Such  a  condition  is 
always  disturbing.  The  old  mental  equilibrium  is  overthrown  and  readjustment 
is  a  slow  process.  Besides,  the  shallow  sense  philosophy  of  that  time  readily  lent 
itself  to  mechanical  and  materialistic  interpretations,  and  for  a  while  it  seemed 
as  if  all  the  higher  faiths  of  humanity  were  permanently  discredited.  All  this  has 
passed  away.  Philosophical  criticism  began  its  work  and  the  naive  dogmatism  of 
materialistic  naturalism  was  soon  disposed  of.  It  quickly  appeared  that  our  trouble 
was  not  due  to  the  new  facts,  but  to  the  superficial  philosophy  by  which  they  had 
been  interpreted.  Now  that  we  have  a  better  philosophy,  we  have  come  to  live  in 
perfect  peace  with  the  facts  once  thought  disturbing,  and  even  to  welcome  them  as 
valuable  additions  to  knowledge.  .  .  . 

The  brief  naturalistic  episode  was  not  without  instruction  for  us.  It  showed 
conclusively  the  great  practical  importance  of  philosophy.  Had  we  had  thirty 
years  ago  the  current  philosophical  insight,  the  great  development  of  the  physical 
and  biological  sciences  would  have  made  no  disturbance  whatever.  But  being 
interpreted  by  a  crude  scheme  of  thought,  it  produced  somewhat  of  a  storm. 
Philosophy  may  not  contribute  much  of  positive  value,  but  it  certainly  has  an 
important  negative  fimction  in  the  way  of  suppressing  pretentious  dogmatism 
and  fictitious  knowledge,  which  often  lead  men  astray.  It  is  these  things  which 
produce  conflicts  of  science  and  religion  or  which  find  in  evolution  the  solvent  of 
all  mysteries  and  the  source  of  all  knowledge. 

Concerning  the  partition  of  territory  between  science  and  philosophy,  there 
are  two  distinct  questions  respecting  the  facts  of  experience.  First,  we  need  to 
know  the  facts  in  their  temporal  and  spatial  order,  and  the  way  they  hang  together 
in  a  system  of  law.  To  get  this  knowledge  is  the  function  of  science,  and  in  this 
work  science  has  Inalienable  rights  and  a  most  important  practical  function.  This 
work  cannot  be  done  by  speculation  nor  interfered  with  by  authority  of  any  kind. 
It  is  not  surprising,  then,  that  scientists  in  their  sense  of  contact  with  reality 


172  PHILOSOPHY 

should  be  indignant  with,  or  feel  contempt  for,  any  who  seek  to  limit  or  proscribe 
their  research.  But  supposing  this  work  all  done,  there  remains  another  question 
respecting  the  causality  and  interpretation  of  the  facts.  This  question  belongs  to 
philosophy.  Science  describes  and  registers  the  facts  with  their  temporal  and 
spatial  laws;  philosophy  studies  their  causality  and  significance.  And  while  the 
scientist  justly  ignores  the  philosopher  who  interferes  with  his  inquiries,  so  the 
philosopher  may  justly  reproach  the  scientist  who  fails  to  see  that  the  scientific 
question  does  not  touch  the  philosophic  one.  .  .  . 

In  the  field  of  metaphysics  proper  I  note  a  strong  tendency  toward  personal 
idealism,  or  as  it  might  be  called,  Personalism;  that  is,  the  doctrine  that  sub- 
stantial reality  can  be  conceived  only  under  the  personal  form  and  that  all  else  is 
phenomenal.  This  is  quite  distinct  from  the  traditional  idealisms  of  mere  concep- 
tionism.  It  holds  the  essential  fact  to  be  a  community  of  persons  with  a  Supreme 
Person  at  their  head  whUe  the  phenomenal  world  is  only  expression  and  means 
of  communication.  And  to  this  view  we  are  led  by  the  failure  of  philosophizing  on 
the  impersonal  plane,  which  is  sure  to  lose  itself  in  contradiction  and  impossi- 
bility. Under  the  form  of  mechanical  naturalism,  with  its  tendencies  to  mate- 
riahsm  and  atheism,  impersonalism  has  once  more  been  judged  and  found  want- 
ing. We  are  not  Ukely  to  have  a  recurrence  of  this  view  imless  there  be  a  return 
to  philosophical  barbarism.  But  impersonalism  at  the  opposite  pole  in  the  form 
of  abstract  categories  of  being,  causahty,  unity,  identity,  continuity,  sufficient 
reason,  etc.,  is  equally  untenable.  Criticism  shows  that  these  categories  when 
abstractly  and  impersonally  taken  cancel  themselves.  On  the  impersonal  plane  we 
can  never  reach  unity  from  plurality,  or  pluraMty  from  unity;  and  we  can  never 
find  change  in  identity,  or  identity  in  change.  Continuity  in  time  becomes  mere 
succession  without  the  notion  of  potentiality,  and  this  in  turn  is  empty.  Exist- 
ence itself  is  dispersed  into  nothingness  through  the  infinite  divisibility  of  space 
and  time,  while  the  law  of  the  sufficient  reason  loses  itself  in  barren  tautology  and 
the  infinite  regress.  The  necessary  logical  equivalence  of  cause  and  effect  in  any 
impersonal  scheme  makes  all  real  explanation  and  progress  impossible,  and  shuts 
us  up  to  an  unintelligible  oscillation  between  potentiahty  and  actuality,  to  which 
there  is  no  corresponding  thought.  .  .  . 

Philosophy  is  still  mihtant  and  has  much  work  before  it,  but  the  omens  are 
auspicious,  the  problems  are  better  understood,  and  we  are  coming  to  a  synthesis 
of  the  results  of  past  generations  of  thinking  which  wiU  be  a  very  distinct  progress. 
Philosophy  has  aheady  done  good  service,  and  never  better  than  in  recent  times, 
by  destroying  pretended  knowledge  and  making  room  for  the  higher  faiths  of 
humanity.  It  has  also  done  good  service  in  helping  these  faiths  to  better  rational 
form,  and  thus  securing  them  against  the  defilements  of  superstition  and  the 
cavilings  of  hostile  critics.  With  aU  its  aberrations  and  shortcomings,  philosophy 
deserves  well  of  humanity. 


FUNDAMENTAL  METHODS  AND   CONCEPTIONS     173 

PHILOSOPHY:    ITS   FUNDAMENTAL   CONCEPTIONS    AND 

ITS   METHODS 

BY    GEORGE    HOLMES   HOWISON 

[George  Holmes  Howison,  Mills  Professor  of  Intellectual  and  Moral  Philo- 
sophy and  Civil  Polity,  University  of  California,  b.  Montgomery  County, 
Maryland,  1834.  A.B.  Marietta  College,  1852  ;  M.A.  1855  ;  LL.D.  ibid. 
1883.  Post-graduate,  Lane  Theological  Seminary,  University  of  Berlin, 
and  Oxford.  Headmaster  High  School,  Salem,  Mass.,  1862-64;  Assistant 
Professor  of  Mathematics,  Washington  University,  St.  Louis,  1864-66;  Tile- 
ston  Professor  of  Political  Economy,  ibid.  1866-69;  Professor  of  Logic  and 
the  Philosophy  of  Science,  Massachusetts  Institute  of  Technology,  1871-79; 
Lecturer  on  Ethics,  Harvard  University,  1879-80;  Lecturer  on  Logic  and 
Speculative  Philosophy,  University  of  Michigan,  1883-84.  Member  and  vice- 
president  St.  Louis  Philosophical  Society;  member  California  Historical 
Society;  American  Historical  Association;  American  Association  for  the 
Advancement  of  Science  ;  National  Geographic  Society,  etc.  Author  of 
Treatise  on  Analytic  Geometry,  1869;  The  Limits  of  Evolution,  1901,  2d  edi- 
tion, 1904;  joint  author  and  editor  of  The  Conception  of  God,  1897,  etc.  Editor 
Philosophical  Publications  of  University  of  California;  American  Editorial 
Representative  Hibbert  Journal,  London.] 

The  duty  has  been  assigned  me,  honored  colleagues,  of  address- 
ing you  on  the  Fundamental  Conceptions  and  the  Methods  of  our 
common  pursuit  —  philosophy.  In  endeavoring  to  deal  with  the 
subject  in  a  way  not  unworthy  of  its  depth  and  its  extent,  I  have 
found  it  impossible  to  bring  the  essential  material  within  less  com- 
pass than  would  occupy,  in  reading,  at  least  four  times  the  period 
granted  by  our  programme.  I  have  therefore  complied  with  the  rule 
of  the  Congress  which  directs  that,  if  a  more  extended  writing  be 
left  with  the  authorities  for  publication,  the  reading  must  be  re- 
stricted to  such  a  portion  of  it  as  will  not  exceed  the  allotted  time. 
I  will  accordingly  read  to  you,  first,  a  brief  summary  of  my  entire 
discussion,  by  way  of  introduction,  and  then  an  excerpt  from  the 
larger  document,  which  may  serve  for  a  specimen,  as  our  scholastic 
predecessors  used  to  say,  of  the  whole  inquiry  I  have  carried  out. 
The  impression  will,  of  course,  be  fragmentary,  and  I  must  'ask 
beforehand  for  your  most  benevolent  allowances,  to  prevent  a  judg- 
ment too  unfavorable. 

The  discussion  naturally  falls  into  two  main  parts:  the  first 
dealing  with  the  Fundamental  Conceptions;  and  the  second,  with 
the  Methods. 

In  the  former,   after  presenting  the   conception  of  philosophy 
itself,  as  the  consideration  of  things  in  the  light  of  the  whole,  I  take  up 
the  involved  Fundamental  Concepts  in  the  following  order :  — 
I.  Whole  and  Part; 

II.  Subject  and  Object  (Knowing  and  Being,  Mind  and  Matter; 
Dualism,  Materialism,  Idealism); 

III.  Reality  and  Appearance  (Noumenon  and  Phenomenon); 


174  PHILOSOPHY 

IV.  Cause  and  Effect  (Ground  and  Consequence;  Causal  System); 
V.  One  and  Many  (Number  System;   Monism  and  Pluralism); 

VI.  Time  and  Space  (their  relation  to  Number;  their  Origin  and 

Ileal  Meaning) ; 
VII.  Unconditioned  and  Conditioned   (Soul,   World,   God;    their 
Reinterpretation  in  terms  of  Pluralism) ; 
VIII.  The    True,  the  Beautiful,  the  Good   (their  relation    to  the 
question  between  Monism  and  Pluralism) . 

These  are  successively  dealt  with  as  they  rise  one  out  of  the  other 
in  the  process  of  interpreting  them  and  applying  them  in  the  actual 
creation  of  philosophy,  as  this  goes  on  in  the  historic  schools.  The 
theoretic  progress  of  philosophy  is  in  this  way  explained  by  them, 
in  its  movement  from  natural  dualism,  or  realism,  through  the 
successive  forms  of  monism,  materialistic,  agnostic,  and  idealistic, 
until  it  reaches  the  issue,  now  coming  so  strongly  forward  within 
the  school  of  idealism,  between  the  adherents  of  monism  and  those 
of  pluralism. 

The  importance  of  the  Fundamental  Concepts  is  shown  to  increase 
as  we  pass  along  the  list,  till  on  reaching  Cause  and  Effect,  and 
entering  upon  its  full  interpretation  into  the  complete  System  of 
Causes,  we  arrive  at  the  very  significant  conception  of  the  Reci- 
procity OF  First  Causes,  and  through  it  come  to  the  Primacy  of 
Final  Cause,  and  the  derivative  position  of  the  other  forms  of  cause, 
Material,  Formal,  Efficient.  The  philosophic  strength  of  idealism, 
but  especially  of  idealistic  pluralism,  comes  into  clear  light  as  the  re- 
sult of  this  stage  of  the  inquiry.  But  it  appears  yet  more  decidedly 
when  One  and  Many,  Time  and  Space,  and  their  interrelations, 
are  subjected  to  analysis.  So  the  discussion  next  passes  to  the 
higher  conceptions.  Soul,  World,  God,  by  the  pathway  of  the  cor- 
relation Unconditioned  and  Conditioned,  and  its  kindred  contrasts 
Absolute  and  Relative,  Necessary  and  Contingent,  Infinite  and 
Finite,  corroborating  and  reinforcing  the  import  of  idealism,  and, 
still  more  decidedly,  that  of  its  plural  form.  Finally,  the  strong 
and  favorable  bearing  of  this  last  on  the  dissolution  of  agnosticism 
and  the  habilitation  of  the  ideals,  the  True,  the  Beautiful,  and  the 
Good,  in  a  heightened  meaning,  is  brought  out. 

This  carries  the  inquiry  to  the  second  part  of  it,  that  of  the  Philo- 
sophical Methods.  Here  I  recount  these  in  a  series  of  six:  the 
Dogmatic,  the  Skeptical,  the  Critical,  the  Pragmatic,  the  Genetic, 
the  Dialectic.  These,  I  show,  in  spite  of  the  tendency  of  the  earlier 
members  in  the  series  to  over-emphasis,  all  have  their  place  and 
function  in  the  development  of  a  complete  philosophy,  and  in  fact 
form  an  ascending  series  in  methodic  effectiveness,  all  that  precede 
the  last  being  taken  up  into  the  comprehensive  Critical  Rationalism 
of  the  last.    Methodology  thus  passes  upward,  over  the  ascending 


FUNDAMENTAL  CONCEPTIONS   AND   METHODS     175 

and  widening  roadways  of  (1)  Intuition  and  Deduction;  (2)  Ex- 
perience and  Induction;  (3)  Intuition  and  Experience  adjusted  by 
Critical  Limits;  (4)  Skepticism  reinforced  and  made  gwast-affirm- 
ative  by  Desire  and  Will;  (5)  Empiricism  enlarged  by  substitu- 
tion of  cosmic  and  psychic  history  for  subjective  consciousness; 
(6)  Enlightened  return  to  a  Rationalism  critically  established  by 
the  inclusion  of  the  preceding  elements,  and  by  the  sifting  and  the 
grading  of  the  Fundamental  Concepts  through  their  behavior  when 
tested  by  the  effort  to  make  them  universal.  In  this  way,  the 
methods  fall  into  a  System,  the  organic  principle  of  which  is  this 
principle  of  Dialectic,  which  proves  itself  alone  able  to  establish 
necessary  truths;  that  is,  truths  indeed,  —  judgments  that  are  seen 
to  exclude  their  opposites,  because,  in  the  attempt  to  substitute  the 
opposite,  the  place  of  it  is  still  filled  by  the  judgment  which  it  aims 
to  dislodge. 

And  now,  with  your  favoring  leave,  I  will  read  the  excerpt  from 
my  larger  text.  ^ 

The  task  to  which,  in  an  especial  sense,  the  cultivators  of  philo- 
sophy are  summoned  by  the  plans  of  the  present  Congress  of  Arts 
and  Science,  is  certainly  such  as  to  stir  an  ambition  to  achieve  it. 
At  the  same  time,  it  tempers  eagerness  by  its  vast  difficulty,  and  the 
apprehension  lest  this  may  prove  insuperable.  The  task,  the  officers 
of  the  Congress  tell  us,  is  no  less  than  to  promote  the  unification  of 
all  human  knowledge.  It  requires,  then,  the  reduction  of  the  enor- 
mous detail  in  our  present  miscellany  of  sciences  and  arts,  which  to 
a  general  glance,  or  even  to  a  more  intimate  view,  presents  a  con- 
fusion of  differences  that  seems  overwhelming,  to  a  system  never- 
theless clearly  harmonious,  —  founded,  that  is  to  say,  upon  uni- 
versal principles  which  control  all  differences  by  explaining  them, 
and  which  therefore,  in  the  last  resort,  themselves  flow  lucidly  from 
a  single  supreme  principle.  Simply  to  state  this  meaning  of  the  task 
set  us,  is  enough  to  awaken  the  doubt  of  its  practicability. 

This  doubt,  we  are  bound  to  confess,  has  more  and  more  impressed 
itself  upon  the  general  mind,  the  farther  this  has  advanced  in  the 
experience  of  scientific  discovery.  The  very  increase  in  the  multi- 
plicity and  complexity  of  facts  and  their  causal  groupings  increases 
the  feeling  that  at  the  root  of  things  there  is  "  a  final  inexplicability  " 
—  total  reality  seems,  more  and  more,  too  vast,  too  profound,  for  us 
to  grasp  or  to  fathom.  And  yet,  strangely  enough,  this  increasing 
sense  of  mysterious  vastness  has  not  in  the  least  prevented  the  modern 
mind  from  more  and  .more  asserting,  with  a  steadily  increasing  in- 
sistence, the  essential  and  unchangeable  unity  of  that  whole  of  things 
which  to  our  ordinary  experience,  and  even  to  all  our  sciences,  appears 
such  an  endless  and  impenetrable  complex  of  differences,  —  yes,  of 
contradictions.  In  fact,  this  assertion  of  the  unity  of  all  things,  under 


176  PHILOSOPHY 

the  favorite  name  of  the  Unity  of  Nature,  is  the  pet  dogma  of  modern 
science;  or,  rather,  to  speak  with  right  accuracy,  it  is  the  stock-in- 
trade  of  a  philosophy  of  science,  current  among  many  of  the  leaders 
of  modern  science;  for  every  such  assertion,  covering,  as  it  tacitly 
and  unavoidably  does,  a  view  about  the  absolute  whole,  is  an  asser- 
tion belonging  to  the  province  of  philosophy,  before  whose  tribunal 
it  must  come  for  the  assessment  of  its  value.  The  presuppositions 
of  all  the  special  sciences,  and,  above  all,  this  presupposition  of  the 
Unity  and  Uniformity  of  Nature,  common  to  all  of  them,  must  thus 
come  back  for  justification  and  requisite  definition  to  philosophy  — 
that  uppermost  and  all-inclusive  form  of  cognition  which  addresses 
itself  to  the  whole  as  whole.  In  their  common  assertion  of  the  Unity 
of  Nature,  the  exponents  of  modern  science  come  unawares  out  of 
their  own  province  into  quite  another  and  a  higher;  and  in  doing  so 
they  show  how  unawares  they  come,  by  presenting  in  most  instances 
the  curious  spectacle  of  proclaiming  at  once  their  increasing  belief 
in  the  unity  of  things,  and  their  increasing  disbelief  in  its  pene- 
trability by  our  intelligence :  — 

In's  Innere  der  Natur, 
Dringt  kein  erschaffner  Geist, 

is  their  chosen  poet's  expression  of  their  philosophic  mood.  Curious 
we  have  the  right  to  call  this  state  of  the  scientific  mind,  because 
it  is  to  critical  reflection  so  certainly  self-contradictory.  How  can 
there  be  a  real  unity  belonging  to  what  is  inscrutable?  —  what  evi- 
dence of  unity  can  there  be,  except  in  intelligible  and  explanatory 
continuity? 

But,  at  all  events,  this  ver}^  mood  of  agnostic  self-contradiction, 
into  which  the  development  of  the  sciences  casts  such  a  multitude 
of  minds,  brings  them,  —  brings  all  of  us,  —  as  already  indicated, 
into  that  court  of  philosophy  where  alone  such  issues  lawfully  belong, 
and  where  alone  they  can  be  adjudicated.  If  the  unification  of  the 
sciences  can  be  made  out  to  be  real  by  making  out  its  sole  sufficient 
condition,  namely,  that  there  is  a  genuine,  and  not  a  merely  nominal, 
unity  in  the  whole  of  reality  itself,  —  a  unity  that  explains  because 
it  is  itself,  not  simply  intelligible,  but  the  only  completely  intelligible 
of  things,  —  this  desirable  result  must  be  the  work  of  philosophy. 
However  difficult  the  task  may  be,  it  is  rightly  put  upon  us  who  belong 
to  the  Department  listed  first  among  the  twenty-four  in  the  pro- 
gramme of  this  representative  Congress. 

I  cannot  but  express  my  own  satisfaction,  as  a  member  of  this 
Department,  nor  fail  to  extend  my  congratulations  to  you  who  are 
my  colleagues  in  it,  that  the  Congress,  in  its  programme,  takes 
openly  the  affirmative  on  this  question  of  the  possible  unification  of 
knowledge.     The  Congress  has  thus  declared  beforehand  for  the 


FUNDAMENTAL   CONCEPTIONS  AND   METHODS    177 

practicability  of  the  task  it  sets.  It  has  even  declared  for  its  not 
distant  accomplishment;  indeed,  not  impossibly,  its  accomplishment 
through  the  transactions  of  the  Congress  itself;  and  it  indicates,  by 
no  uncertain  signs,  the  leading,  the  determining  part  that  philosophy 
must  have  in  the  achievement.  In  fact,  the  authorities  of  the  Congress 
themselves  suggest  a  solution  of  their  own  for  their  problem.  In  their 
programme  we  see  a  renewed  Hierarchy  of  the  Sciences,  and  at  the 
summit  of  this  appears  now  again,  after  so  long  a  period  of  humiliating 
obscuration,  the  figure  of  Philosophy,  raised  anew  to  that  supremacy, 
as  Queen  of  the  Sciences,  which  had  been  hers  from  the  days  of  Plato 
to  those  of  Copernicus,  but  which  she  began  to  lose  when  modern 
physical  and  historical  research  entered  upon  its  course  of  sudden 
development,  and  which,  until  recently,  she  has  continued  more  and 
more  to  lose  as  the  sciences  have  advanced  in  their  career  of  discover- 
ies, —  ever  more  unexpected,  more  astonishing,  yet  more  convincing 
and  more  helpful  to  the  welfare  of  mankind.  May  this  sign  of  her 
recovered  empire  not  fail!  If  we  rejoice  at  the  token,  the  Congress 
has  made  it  our  part  to  see  that  the  title  is  vindicated.  It  is  ours  to 
show  this  normative  function  of  philosophy,  this  power  to  reign  as  the 
unifying  discipline  in  the  entire  realm  of  our  possible  knowledge;  to 
show  it  by  showing  that  the  very  nature  of  philosophy  —  its  ele- 
mental concepts  and  its  directing  ideals^  its  methods  taken  in  their 
systematic  succession  —  is  such  as  must  result  in  a  view  of  universal 
reality  that  will  supply  the  principle  at  once  giving  rise  to  all  the 
sciences  and  connecting  them  all  into  one  harmonious  whole. 

Such,  and  so  grave,  my  honored  colleagues,  is  the  duty  assigned  to 
this  hour.  Sincerely  can  I  say.  Would  it  had  fallen  to  stronger  hands 
than  mine!  But  since  to  mine  it  has  been  committed,  I  will  undertake 
it  in  no  disheartened  spirit;  rather,  in  that  temper  of  animated  hope 
in  which  the  whole  Congress  has  been  conceived  and  planned.  And 
I  draw  encouragement  from  the  place,  and  its  associations,  where 
we  are  assembled  —  from  its  historic  connections  not  only  with  the 
external  expansion  of  our  country,  but  with  its  growth  in  culture, 
and  especially  with  its  growth  in  the  cultivation  of  philosophy.  For 
your  speaker,  at  least,  can  never  forget  that  here  in  St.  Louis,  the 
metropolis  of  the  region  by  which  our  national  domain  was  in  the 
Louisiana  Purchase  so  enlarged,  —  here  was  the  centre  of  a  move- 
ment in  philosophic  study  that  has  proved  to  be  of  national  import. 
It  is  fitting  that  we  all,  here  to-day,  near  to  the  scene  itself,  com- 
memorate the  public  service  done  by  our  present  National  Commis- 
sioner of  Education  and  his  group  of  enthusiastic  associates,  in 
beginning  here,  in  the  middle  years  of  the  preceding  century,  those 
studies  of  Kant  and  his  great  idealistic  successors  that  unexpectedly 
became  the  nucleus  of  a  wider  and  more  penetrating  study  of  philo- 
sophy in  all  parts  of  our  country.    It  is  with  quickened  memories 


178  PHILOSOPHY 

belonging  to  the  spot  where,  more  than  five-and-thirty  years  ago,  it 
was  my  happy  fortune  to  take  some  part  with  Dr.  Harris  and  his 
companions,  that  I  begin  the  task  assigned  me.  The  undertaking 
seems  less  hopeless  when  I  can  here  recall  the  names  and  the  con- 
genial labors  of  Harris,  of  Davidson,  of  Brockmeyer,  of  Snider,  of 
Watters,  of  Jones,  —  half  of  them  now  gone  from  life.  They  "  builded 
better  than  they  knew; "  and,  humbly  as  they  may  themselves  have 
estimated  their  ingenuous  efforts  to  gain  acquaintance  with  the  great- 
est thoughts,  history  will  not  fail  to  take  note  of  what  they  did,  as 
marking  one  of  the  turning-points  in  the  culture  of  our  nation.  The 
publication  of  the  Journal  of  Speculative  Philosophy,  granting  all 
the  subtractions  claimed  by  its  critics  on  the  score  of  defects  (of 
which  its  conductors  were  perhaps  only  too  sensible) ,  was  an  influence 
that  told  in  all  our  circles  of  philosophical  study,  and  thence  in  the 
whole  of  our  social  as  well  as  our  academic  life. 

[Here  I  enter  upon  the  discussion  of  the  subject  proper,  beginning, 
as  above  indicated,  with  the  Fundamental  Conceptions.  Having 
followed  these  through  the  contrasts  Whole  and  Part,  Subject  and 
Object,  Reality  and  Appearance  (or  Noumenon  and  Phenomenon), 
and  developed  the  bearing  of  these  on  the  procedure  of  thought  from 
the  dualism  of  natural  realism  to  materialism  and  thence  to  idealism, 
with  the  issue  now  coming  on,  in  this  last,  between  monism  and 
pluralism,  I  strike  into  the  contrast  Cause  and  Effect,  and,  noting 
its  unfolding  into  the  more  comprehensive  form  of  Ground  and  Con- 
sequence, go  on  thence  as  follows :  ] 

It  is  plain  that  the  contrast  Ground  and  Consequence  will  enable 
us  to  state  the  new  issue  with  closer  precision  and  pertinence  than 
Reality  and  Appearance,  Noumenon  and  Phenomenon,  can  supply; 
while,  at  the  same  time.  Ground  and  Consequence  exhibits  Cause  and 
Effect  as  presenting  a  contrast  that  only  fulfills  what  Noumenon  and 
Phenomenon  foretold  and  strove  towards;  in  fact,  what  was  more 
remotely,  but  not  less  surely,  also  indicated  by  Whole  and  Part, 
Knowing  and  Being,  Subject  and  Object.  For  in  penetrating  to  the 
coherent  meaning  of  these  conceptions,  the  philosophic  movement, 
as  we  saw,  advanced  steadily  to  the  fuller  and  fuller  translating  of 
each  of  them  into  the  reality  that  unifies  by  explanation,  instead  of 
pretending  to  explain  by  merely  unifying;  and  this,  of  course,  will 
now  be  put  forward  explicitly,  in  the  clarified  category  of  Cause  and 
Effect,  transfigured  from  a  physical  into  a  purely  logical  relation. 
What  idealism  now  says,  in  terms  of  this,  is  that  the  Cause  (or,  as 
we  now  read  it,  the  Ground)  of  all  that  exists  is  the  Subject;  is 
Mind,  the  intelligently  Self-conscious;  and  that  all  things  else,  the 
mere  objects,  material  things,  are  its  Consequence,  its  Outcome,  — 


FUNDAMENTAL   CONCEPTIONS  AND   METHODS     179 

in  that  sense  its  Effect.  And  what  the  new  phiraHstic  ideahsm  says, 
is  that  the  assemblage  of  individual  minds  —  intelligence  being 
essentially  personal  and  individual,  and  never  merely  universal 
and  collective  —  is  the  true  total  Cause  of  all,  and  that  every  mind 
thus  belongs  to  the  order  of  First  Causes;  nevertheless,  that  part, 
and  the  most  significant  part,  of  the  nature  of  ever}^  mind,  essential 
to  its  personality  and  its  reason,  is  its  recognition  of  other  minds  in 
the  very  act  of  its  own  self -definition.  That  is  to  say,  a  mind  by  its 
spontaneous  nature  as  intelligence,  by  its  intrinsic  rational  or  logical 
genius,  puts  itself  as  member  of  a  system  of  minds;  all  minds  are  put 
by  each  other  as  Ends  —  completely  standard  and  sacred  Objects, 
as  much  parts  of  the  system  of  true  Causes  as  each  is,  in  its  capacity 
of  Subject;  and  we  have  a  noumenal  Reality  that  is  properly  to  be 
described  as  the  eternal  Federal  Republic  of  Spirits. 

Consequently,  the  relation  of  Cause  and  Effect  now  expands  and 
heightens  into  a  sj^'stem  of  the  Reciprocity  of  First  Causes;  causes, 
that  is,  which,  while  all  coefficients  in  the  existence  and  explanation 
of  that  natural  world  of  experience  which  forms  their  passive  effect, 
their  objects  of  mere  perception,  are  themselves  related  only  in  the 
higher  way  of  Final  Causes  —  that  is,  Defining-Bases  and  Ends  — 
of  each  other,  making  them  the  logical  Complements,  and  the  Ob- 
jects of  conduct,  all  for  each,  and  each  for  all.  Hence,  the  system 
of  causation  undergoes  a  signal  transformation,  and  proves  to  be 
organized  by  Final  Cause  as  its  basis  and  root,  instead  of  by  Efficient 
Cause,  or  Originating  Ground,  as  the  earlier  stages  of  thinking  had 
always  assumed. 

The  causal  relation  between  the  absolute  or  primary  realities 
being  purely  Final,  or  Defining  and  Purposive;  that  is  to  say,  the 
uncoercive  influence  of  recognition  and  ideality;  all  the  other  forms 
of  cause,  as  grouped  by  Aristotle,  —  Material,  Formal,  and  Efficient, 
—  are  seen  to  be  the  derivatives  of  Final  Cause,  as  being  supphed 
by  the  action  of  the  minds  that,  as  absolute  or  underived  realities, 
exist  only  in  the  relation  of  mutual  Complements  and  Ends.  Accord- 
ingly, Efficient  Cause  operates  only  from  minds,  as  noumena,  to 
matter,  as  their  phenomenon,  their  presented  contents  of  experience; 
or,  in  a  secondary  and  derivative  sense,  from  one  phenomenon  to 
another,  or  from  one  group  of  phenomena  to  another  group,  these 
playing  the  part  of  transmitters,  or  (as  some  logicians  would  say) 
Instrumental  Causes,  or  Means.  Cause,  as  Material,  is  hence  defined 
as  the  elementary  phenomenon,  and  the  combinations  of  this;  and 
therefore,  strictly  taken,  is  merely  Effect  (or  Outcome)  of  the  self- 
active  consciousness,  whose  spontaneous  forms  of  conception  and 
perception  become  the  Formal  Cause  that  organizes  the  sum  of 
phenomena  into  cosmic  harmony  or  unity. 


180  PHILOSOPHY 

Here,  accordingly,  comes  into  view  the  further  and  in  some  respects 
deeper  conceptual  pair,  Many  and  One.  The  history  of  philosophic 
thought  proves  that  this  antithesis  is  darkly  obscure  and  deeply 
ambiguous;  for  about  it  have  centred  a  large  part  of  the  conflicts 
of  doctrine.  This  pair  has  already  been  used,  implicitly,  in  exhibiting 
the  development  of  the  preceding  group,  Cause  and  Effect;  and 
in  so  using  it  we  have  supplied  ourselves  with  a  partial  clarification 
of  it,  and  with  one  possible  solution  of  its  ambiguity.  We  have  seen, 
namely,  how  our  strong  natural  persuasion  that  philosophy  guided 
by  the  fundamental  concept  Cause  must  become  the  search  for  the 
One  amid  the  wilderness  of  the  Many,  and  that  this  search  cannot 
be  satisfied  and  ended  except  in  an  all-inclusive  Unit,  in  which  the 
Many  is  embraced  as  the  integral  and  originated  parts,  completely 
determined,  subjected,  and  controlled,  may  give  way  to  another 
and  less  oppressive  conception  of  unity;  a  conception  of  it  as  the 
harmony  among  many  free  and  independent  primary  realities, 
a  harmony  founded  on  their  intelligent  and  reasonable  mutual 
recognition.  This  conception  casts  at  least  some  clearing  light  upon 
the  long  and  dreary  disputes  over  the  Many  and  the  One;  for  it 
exposes,  plainly,  the  main  source  of  them.  They  have  arisen  out  of 
two  chief  ambiguities, — the  ambiguity  of  the  concept  One,  and  the 
ambiguity  of  the  concept  Cause  in  its  supreme  meaning.  The  normal 
contrast  between  the  One  and  the  Many  is  a  clear  and  simple  con- 
trast: the  One  is  the  single  unit,  and  the  Many  is  the  repetition  of 
the  unit,  or  is  the  collection  of  the  several  units.  But  if  we  go  on  to 
suppose  that  there  is  a  collection  or  sum  oi  all  possible  units,  and 
call  this  the  Wliole,  then,  since  there  can  'be  no  second  such,  we  call 
it  also  "one"  (or  the  One,  by  way  of  preeminence),  overlooking  the 
fact  that  it  differs  from  the  simple  one,  or  unit,  in  genere;  that  it  is 
in  fact  not  a  unit  at  all,  not  an  elementary  member  of  a  series,  but 
the  annulment  of  all  series;  that  our  name  "one"  has  profoundly 
changed  its  meaning,  and  now  stands  for  the  Sole,  the  Only.  Thus, 
by  our  forgetfulness  of  differences,  we  fall  into  deep  water,  and, 
with  the  confused  illusions  of  the  drowning,  dream  of  the  One  and 
All  as  the  single  punctum  originatioms  of  all  things,  the  Source  and 
Begetter  of  the  very  imits  of  which  it  is  in  reality  only  the  resultant 
and  tTie  derivative.  Or,  from  another  point  of  view,  and  in  another 
mood,  we  riglitly  enough  take  the  One  to  mean  the  coherent,  the 
intelligible,  the  consistent,  the  harmonious;  and  putting  the  Many, 
on  the  misleading  hint  of  its  contrast  to  the  unit,  in  antithesis  to 
this  One  of  harmony,  we  fall  into  the  ?belief  that  the  Many  cannot 
be  harmonious,  is  intrinsically  a  cluster  of  repulsions  or  of  collisions, 
incapable  of  giving  rise  to  accord;  indeed,  essentially  hostile  to  it. 
So,  as  accord  is  the  aim  and  the  essence  of  our  reason,  we  are  caught 
in  the  snare  of  monism,  pluralism  having  apparently  become  the 


FUNDAMENTAL  CONCEPTIONS  AND   METHODS     181 

equivalent  of  chaos,  and  thus  the  bete  noir  of  rational  metaphysics. 
Nay,  in  the  opposed  camp  itself,  some  of  the  most  ardent  adherents 
of  pluralism,  the  hveliest  of  wit,  the  most  exuberant  in  literary  re- 
sources, are  the  abjectest  believers  in  the  hopeless  disjunction  and 
capriciousness  of  the  plural,  and  hold  there  is  a  rift  in  the  texture  of 
reality  that  no  intelligence,  "  even  though  you  dub  it '  the  Absolute,' " 
can  mend  or  reach  across.  Yet  surely  there  is  nothing  in  the  Many,  as 
a  sum  of  units,  the  least  at  war  with  the  One  as  a  system  of  harmony. 
On  the  contrary,  even  in  the  pure  form  of  the  Number  Series,  the 
Many  is  impossible  except  on  the  principle  of  harmony,  —  the  units 
can  be  collected  and  summed  (that  is,  constitute  the  Many),  only 
if  they  cohere  in  a  community  of  intrinsic  kindred.  Consequently 
the  whole  question  of  the  chaotic  or  the  harmonic  nature  of  a  plural 
world  turns  on  the  nature  of  the  genus  which  we  find  characteristic 
of  the  absolutely  (le.,  the  unreservedly)  real,  and  which  is  to  be  taken 
as  the  common  denomination  enabling  us  to  count  them  and  to  sum 
them.  When  minds  are  seen  to  be  necessarily  the  primary  realities, 
but  also  necessarily  federal  as  well  as  individual,  the  illusion  about 
the  essential  disjunction  and  non-coherence  of  the  plurally  real  dis- 
solves away,  and  a  primordial  world  of  manifold  persons  is  seen 
to  involve  no  fundamental  or  hopeless  anarchy  of  individualism, 
irreducible  in  caprice,  but  an  indwelling  principle  of  harmony, 
rather,  that  from  the  springs  of  individual  being  intends  the  control 
and  composure  of  all  the  disorders  that  mark  the  world  of  experien- 
tial appearance,  and  so  must  tend  perpetually  to  effect  this. 

The  other  main  source  of  our  confusions  over  the  Many  and  the 
One  is  the  variety  of  meaning  hidden  in  the  concept  Cause,  and  our 
propensity  to  take  its  most  obvious  but  least  significant  sense  for 
its  supreme  intent.  Closest  at  hand,  in  experience,  is  our  productive 
causation  of  changes  in  our  sense- world,  and  hence  most  obvious 
is  that  reading  of  Cause  which  takes  it  as  the  producer  of  changes 
and,  with  a  deeper  comprehension  of  it,  of  the  inalterable  linkage 
between  changes,  whereby  one  follows  regularly  and  surely  upon 
another.  Thus  what  we  have  in  philosophy  agreed  to  call  Efficient 
Cause  comes  to  be  mistaken  for  the  profoundest  and  the  supreme  form 
of  cause,  and  all  the  other  modes  of  cause,  the  Material  (or  Stuff), 
the  Form  (or  Conception),  and  the  End  (or  Purpose),  its  conse- 
quent and  derivative  auxiliaries.  Under  the  influence  of  this  strong 
impression,  we  either  assume  total  reality  to  be  One  Whole,  all- 
embracing  and  all-producing  of  its  manifold  modes,  or  else  view  it 
as  a  duality,  consisting  of  One  Creator  and  his  manifold  creatures. 
So  it  has  come  about  that  metaphysics  has  hitherto  been  chiefly 
a  contention  between  pantheism  and  monotheism,  or,  as  the  latter 
should  for  greater  accuracy  be  called,  monarchotheism;  and,  it 
must  be  acknowledged,  this  struggle  has  been  attended  by  a  con- 


182  PHILOSOPHY 

tinued  (though  not  continual)  decline  of  this  later  dualistic  theory 
before  the  steadfast  front  and  unyielding  advance  of  the  older 
monism.  Thus  persistent  has  been  the  assumption  that  harmony  can 
only  be  assured  by  the  unity  given  in  some  single  productive  causa- 
tion :  the  only  serious  uncertainty  has  been  about  the  most  rational 
way  of  conceiving  the  operation  of  this  Sole  Cause;  and  this  doubt 
has  thus  far,  on  the  whole,  declined  in  favor  of  the  Elder  Oriental 
or  monistic  conception,  as  against  the  Hebraic  conception  of  extra- 
neous creation  by  fiat.  The  frankly  confessed  mystery  of  the  latter, 
its  open  appeal  to  miracle,  places  it  at  a  fatal  disadvantage  with  the 
Elder  Orientalism,  when  the  appeal  is  to  reason  and  intelligibility. 
It  is  therefore  no  occasion  for  wonder  that,  especially  since  the  rise 
of  the  scientific  doctrine  of  Evolution,  with  its  postulate  of  a  univer- 
sal unity,  self-varying  yet  self-fulfilling,  even  the  leaders  of  theology 
are  more  and  more  falling  into  the  monistic  line  and  swelling  the 
ever-growing  ranks  of  pantheism.  If  it  be  asked  here,  And  why  not  ? 
—  where  is  the  harm  of  it  ?  —  is  not  the  whole  question  simply  of  what 
is  true?  the  answer  is.  The  mortal  harm  of  the  destruction  of  personal- 
ity, which  lives  or  dies  with  the  preservation  or  destruction  of  individual 
responsibility;  while  the  completer  truth  is,  that  there  are  other  and 
profounder  (or,  if  you  please,  higher)  truths  than  this  of  explanation 
hy  Efficient  Cause.  In  fact,  there  is  a  higher  conception  of  Cause 
itself  than  this  of  production,  or  efficiency;  for,  of  course,  as  we  well 
might  say,  that  alone  can  be  the  supreme  conception  of  Cause  which 
can  subsist  between  absolute  or  unreserved  realities,  and  such  must 
exclude  their  production  or  their  necessitating  control  by  others. 
So  that  we  ought  long  since  to  have  realized  that  Final  Cause,  the 
recognized  presence  to  each  other  as  unconditioned  realities,  or  De- 
fining Auxiliaries  and  Ends,  is  the  sole  causal  relation  that  can  hold 
among  primary  realities;  though  among  such  it  can  hold,  and  in 
fact  must. 

For  the  absolute  reality  of  personal  intelligences,  at  once  indi- 
vidual and  universally  recognizant  of  others,  is  called  for  by  other 
conceptions  fundamental  to  philosophy.  These  other  fundamental 
concepts  can  no  more  be  counted  out  or  ignored  than  those  we  have 
hitherto  considered;  and  when  we  take  them  up,  we  shall  see  how 
vastly  more  significant  they  are.  They  alone  will  prove  supreme, 
truly  organizing,  normative;  they  alone  can  introduce  gradation  in 
truths,  for  they  alone  introduce  the  judgment  of  worth,  of  valuation; 
they  alone  can  give  us  counsels  of  perfection,  for  they  alone  rise 
from  those  elements  in  our  being  which  deal  with  ideals  and  with 
veritable  Ideas.    So  let  us  proceed  to  them. 

Our  path  into  their  presence,  however,  is  through  another  pair, 
not  so  plainly  antithetic  as  those  we  have  thus  far  considered.    This 


FUNDAMENTAL   CONCEPTIONS  AND   METHODS    183 

pair  that  I  now  mean  is  Time  and  Space,  which,  though  not  ob- 
viously antinomic,  yet  owes  its  existence,  as  can  now  be  shown, 
to  that  profoundest  of  concept-contrasts  which  we  earlier  considered 
under  the  head  of  Subject  and  Object,  when  the  Object  takes  on  its 
only  adequate  form  of  Other  Subject.  But  in  passing  from  the  con- 
trast One  and  Many  towards  its  rational  transformation  into  the 
moral  society  of  Mind  and  Companion  Minds,  we  break  into  this 
pair  of  Time  and  Space,  and  must  make  our  way  through  it  by 
taking  in  its  full  meaning. 

Time  and  Space  play  an  enormous  part  in  all  our  empirical  thinking, 
our  actual  use  of  thought  in  our  sense-perceptive  life.  And  no  wonder; 
for,  in  cooperation,  they  form  the  postulate  and  condition  of  all  our 
possible  sensuous  consciousness.  Only  on  them  as  backgrounds  can 
thought  take  on  the  peculiar  clearness  of  an  image  or  a  picture ;  only 
on  the  screens  which  they  supply  can  we  literally  depict  an  object. 
And  this  clarity  of  outline  and  boundary  is  so  dear  to  our  ordinary 
consciousness,  that  we  are  prone  to  say  there  is  no  sufficient,  no  real 
clearness,  unless  we  can  clarify  by  the  bounds  either  of  place  or  of 
date,  or  of  both.  In  this  mood,  we  are  led  to  deny  the  reality  and 
validity  of  thought  altogether,  when  it  cannot  be  defined  in  the  metes 
and  bounds  afforded  by  Time  or  by  Space:  that  which  has  no  date 
nor  place,  we  say,  —  no  extent  and  no  duration,  —  cannot  be  real; 
it  is  but  a  pseudo-thought,  a  pretense  and  a  delusion.  Here  is  the 
extremely  plausible  foundation  of  the  philosophy  known  as  sensa- 
tionism,  the  refined  or  second-thought  form  of  materialism,  in  which 
it  begins  its  euthanasia  into  idealism. 

Without  delaying  here  to  criticise  this,  let  us  notice  the  part  that 
Time  and  Space  play  in  reference  to  the  conceptual  pair  we  last  con- 
sidered, the  One  and  the  Many;  for  not  otherwise  shall  we  find  our 
way  beyond  them  to  the  still  more  fundamental  conceptions  which 
we  are  now  aiming  to  reach.  Indeed,  it  is  through  our  surface-appre- 
hension of  the  pair  One  and  Many,  as  this  illumines  experience,  that 
we  most  naturally  come  at  the  pair  Time  and  Space;  so  that  these  are 
at  first  taken  for  mere  generalizations  and  abstractions,  the  purely 
nominal  representatives  of  the  actual  distinctions  between  the  mem- 
bers of  the  Many  by  our  sense-perception  of  this  from  that,  of  here 
from  there,  of  now  from  then.  It  is  not  till  our  reflective  attention  is 
fixed  on  the  fact  that  there  and  here,  now  and  then,  are  peculiar  dis- 
tinctions, wholly  different  from  other  contrasts  of  this  with  that,  — 
which  may  be  made  in  all  sorts  of  ways,  by  difference  of  quality,  or  of 
quantity,  or  of  relations  quite  other  than  place  and  date,  —  it  is  not 
till  we  realize  this  peculiar  character  of  the  Time-contrast  and  the 
Space-contrast,  that  we  see  these  singular  differential  qualia  cannot 
be  derived  from  others,  not  even  from  the  contrast  One  and  Many, 
but  are  independent,  are  themselves  underived  and  spontaneous 


184  PHILOSOPHY 

utterances  of  our  intelligent,  our  percipient  nature.  But  when  Kant 
jEirst  helped  mankind  to  the  realization  of  this  spontaneous  (or 
a  priori)  character  of  this  pair  of  perceptive  conditions,  or  Sense- 
Forms,  he  fell  into  the  persuasion,  and  led  the  philosophic  world  into 
it,  that  though  Time  and  Space  are  not  derivatives  of  the  One  and 
the  Many  read  as  the  numerical  aspect  of  our  perceptive  experiences, 
yet  there  is  between  the  two  pairs  a  connection  of  dependence  as 
intimate  as  that  first  supposed,  but  in  exactly  the  opposite  sense; 
namely,  that  the  One  and  the  Many  are  conditioned  by  Time  and 
Space,  or,  when  it  comes  to  the  last  resort,  are  at  any  rate  completely 
dependent  upon  Time.  By  a  series  of  units,  this  view  means,  we  really 
understand  a  set  of  items  discriminated  and  related  either  as  points  or 
as  instants:  in  the  last  analysis,  as  instants:  that  is,  it  is  impossible 
to  apprehend  a  unit,  or  to  count  and  sum  units,  unless  the  unit  is  taken 
as  an  instant,  and  the  units  as  so  many  instants.  Numbers,  Kant 
holds,  are  no  doubt  pure  (or  quite  unsensuous)  percepts,  —  dis- 
cerned particulars,  —  therefore  spontaneous  products  of  the  mind 
a  priori,  but  made  possible  only  by  the  primary  pure  percept  Time, 
or,  again,  through  the  mediation  of  this,  by  the  conjoined  pure  per- 
cept Space;  so  that  the  numbers,  in  their  own  pure  character,  are 
simply  the  instants  in  their  series.  As  the  instants,  and  therefore  the 
numbers,  are  pure  percepts,  —  particulars  discerned  without  the 
help  of  sense,  —  so  pure  percepts,  in  a  primal  and  comprehensive 
sense,  argues  Kant,  must  their  conditioning  postulates  Time  and 
Space  be,  to  supply  the  "element,"  or  "medium,"  that  will  render 
such  pure  percepts  possible. 

This  doctrine  of  Kant's  is  certainly  plausible;  indeed,  it  is  impress- 
ively so;  and  it  has  taken  a  vast  hold  in  the  world  of  science,  and 
has  reinforced  the  popular  belief  in  the  unreality  of  thought  apart 
from  Time  and  Space;  an  unreality  which  it  is  an  essential  part  of 
Kant's  system  to  establish  critically.  But  as  a  graver  result,  it  has 
certainly  tended  to  discredit  the  belief  in  personal  identity  as  an 
abiding  and  immutable  reality,  enthroned  over  the  mutations  of 
things  in  Time  and  Space;  since  all  that  is  in  these  is  numbered  and 
is  mutable,  and  is  rather  many  than  one,  yet  nothing  is  believed  real 
except  as  it  falls  under  them,  at  any  rate  under  Time.  And  with  this 
decline  of  the  belief  in  a  changeless  self,  has  declined,  almost  as  rapidly 
and  extensively,  the  belief  in  immortalit3^  Or,  rather,  the  per- 
manence and  the  identity  of  the  person  has  faded  into  a  question 
regarded  as  unanswerable ;  though  none  the  less  does  this  agnostic 
state  of  belief  tend  to  take  personality,  in  any  responsible  sense  of 
the  word,  out  of  the  region  of  practical  concern.  With  what  is  un- 
knowable, even  if  existing,  we  can  have  no  active  traffic;  'tis  for 
our  conduct  as  if  it  were  not. 

So  it  behooves  us  to  search  if  this  prevalent  view  about  the  relation 


FUNDAMENTAL   CONCEPTIONS   AND   METHODS     185 

of  One  and  Many  to  Time  and  Space  is  trustworthy  and  exact.  What 
place  and  function  in  philosophy  must  Space  and  Time  be  given?  — 
for  they  certainly  have  a  place  and  function;  they  certainly  are 
among  the  inexpugnable  conceptions  with  which  thought  has  to 
concern  itself  when  it  undertakes  to  gain  a  view  of  the  whole.  But 
it  may  be  easy  to  give  them  a  larger  place  and  function  than  belong 
to  them  by  right.  Is  it  true,  then,  that  the  One  and  the  Many  —  that 
the  system  of  Numbers,  in  short  —  are  unthinkable  except  as  in 
Space  and  Time,  or,  at  any  rate,  in  Time?  Or,  to  put  the  question 
more  exactly,  as  well  as  more  gravely  and  more  pertinently.  Are 
Space  and  Time  the  true  prindpia  individui,  and  is  Time  preemi- 
nently the  ultimate  prindpium  individuationis  9  Is  there  accordingly 
no  individuality,  and  no  society,  no  associative  assemblage,  except 
in  the  fleeting  world  of  phenomena,  dated  and  placed?  Simply  to  ask 
the  question,  and  thus  bring  out  the  full  drift  of  this  Kantian  doc- 
trine, is  almost  to  expose  the  absurdity  of  it.  Such  a  doctrine,  though 
it  may  be  wisely  refusing  to  confound  personality,  true  individuality, 
with  the  mere  logical  singular;  nay,  worse,  with  a  limited  and  special 
illustration  of  the  singular,  the  one  here  or  the  one  there,  the  one  now 
or  the  one  then  ;  nevertheless,  by  confining  numerability  to  things 
material  and  sensible,  makes  personal  identity  something  unmeaning 
or  impossible,  and  destroys  part  of  the  foundation  for  the  relations 
of  moral  responsibility.  Though  the  vital  trait  of  the  person,  his 
genuine  individuality,  doubtless  lies,  not  in  his  being  exactly  num- 
erable, but  in  his  being  aboriginal  and  originative;  in  a  word,  in  his 
self-activity,  in  his  being  a  centre  of  autonomous  social  recognition; 
yet  exactly  numerable  he  indeed  is,  and  must  be,  not  confusable  with 
any  other,  else  his  professed  autonomy,  his  claim  of  rights  and  his 
sense  of  duty,  can  have  no  significance,  must  vanish  in  the  universal 
confusion  belonging  to  the  indefinite.  Nor,  on  the  other  hand,  is  it  at 
all  true  that  a  number  has  to  be  a  point  or  an  instant,  nor  that  things 
when  numbered  and  counted  are  implicitly  pinned  upon  points  or,  at 
all  events,  upon  instants.  It  may  well  enough  be  the  fact  that  in  our 
empirical  use  of  number  we  have  to  employ  Time,  or  even  Space,  but 
it  is  a  gaping  non  sequitur  to  conclude  that  we  therefore  can  count 
nothing  but  the  placed  and  the  dated.  Certainly  we  count  whenever 
we  distinguish,  —  by  whatever  means,  on  whatever  ground.  To 
think  is,  in  general,  at  least  to  "distinguish  the  things  that  differ;" 
but  this  will  not  avail  except  we  keep  account  of  the  differences; 
hence  the  One  and  the  Many  lie  in  the  very  bosom  of  intelligence, 
and  this  fundamental  -and  spontaneous  contrast  can  not  only  rive 
Time  and  Space  into  expressions  of  it,  in  instants  and  in  points,  but 
travels  with  thought  from  its  start  to  its  goal,  and  as  organic  factor 
in  mathematical  science  does  indeed,  as  Plato  in  the  Republic  said, 
deal  with  absolute  being,  if  yet  dreamwise  ;  so  that  One  and  Many, 


186  PHILOSOPHY 

and  Many  as  the  sum  of  the  ones,  makes  part  of  the  measure  of  that 
primally  real  world  which  the  world  of  minds  alone  can  be.  If  the 
contrast  One  and  Many  can  pass  the  bounds  of  the  merely  phenome- 
nal, by  passing  the  temporal  and  the  spatial;  if  it  applies  to  universal 
being,  to  the  noumenal  as  well  as  to  the  phenomenal;  then  the  abso- 
lutely real  world,  so  far  as  concerns  this  essential  condition,  can  be 
a  world  of  genuine  individuals,  identifiable,  free,  abiding,  responsible, 
and  there  can  be  a  real  moral  order;  if  not,  then  there  can  be  no 
such  moral  world,  and  the  deeper  thought-conceptions  to  which  we 
now  approach  must  be  regarded,  at  the  best,  as  fair  illusions,  bare 
ideals,  which  the  serious  devotee  of  truth  must  shun,  except  in  such 
moments  of  vacancy  and  leisure  as  he  may  venture  to  surrender, 
at  intervals,  to  purely  hedonic  uses.  But  if  the  One  and  the  Many 
are  not  dependent  on  Time  and  Space,  their  universal  validity  is 
possible;  and  it  has  already  been  shown  that  they  are  not  so  de- 
pendent, are  not.  thus  restricted. 

And  now  it  remains  to  show  their  actual  universality,  by  exhibiting 
their  place  in  the  structure  of  the  absolutely  real;  since  nobody  calls 
in  question  their  pertinence  to  the  world  of  phenomena.  But  their 
noumenal  applicability  follows  from  their  essential  implication  with 
all  and  every  difference:  no  difference,  no  distinction,  that  does  not 
carry  counting;  and  this  is  quite  as  true  as  that  there  can  be  no  count- 
ing without  difference.  The  One  and  the  Many  thus  root  in  Identity 
and  Difference,  pass  up  into  fuller  expression  in  Universal  and  Par- 
ticular, hold  forward  into  Cause  and  Effect,  attain  their  commanding 
presentation  in  the  Reciprocity  of  First  Causes,  and  so  keep  record  of 
the  contrast  between  Necessity  and  Contingency.  In  short,  they  are 
founded  in,  and  in  their  turn  help  (indispensably)  to  express,  all  the 
categories,  —  Quality,  Quantity,  Relation,  Modality.  Nor  do  they 
suffer  arrest  there;  they  hold  in  the  ideals,  the  True,  the  Beautiful, 
the  Good,  and  in  the  primary  Ideas,  the  Self,  the  World,- and  God. 
For  all  of  these  differ,  however  close  their  logical  linkage  may  be; 
and  in  so  far  as  they  differ,  each  of  them  is  a  counted  unit,  and  so  they 
are  many.  And,  most  profoundly  of  all,  One  and  Many  take  footing 
in  absolute  reality  so  soon  as  we  realize  that  nothing  short  of  intelli- 
gent being  can  be  primordially  real,  underived,  and  truly  causal,  and 
that  intelligence  is,  by  its  idea,  at  once  an  /-thinking  and  a  universal 
recognizant  outlook  upon  others  that  think  7. 

Hence  Number,  so  far  from  being  the  derivative  of  Time  and  Space, 
founds,  at  the  bottom,  in  the  self-definition  and  social  recognition  of 
intelligent  beings,  and  so  finds  a  priori  a  valid  expression  in  Time  and 
in  Space,  as  well  as  in  every  other  primitive  and  spontaneous  form  in 
which  intelligence  utters  itself.  The  Pythagorean  doctrine  of  the  rank 
of  Number  in  the  scale  of  realities  is  only  one  remove  from  the  truth : 
though  the  numbers  are  indeed  not  the  Prime  Beings,  they  do  enter 


FUNDAMENTAL  CONCEPTIONS   AND   METHODS     187 

into  the  essential  nature  of  the  Prime  Beings;  are^  so  to  speak,  the 
organ  of  their  definite  reality  and  identity,  and  for  that  reason  go 
forward  into  the  entire  defining  procedure  by  which  these  intelli- 
gences organize  their  world  of  experiences.  And  the  popular  impres- 
sion that  Time  and  Space  are  derivatives  from  Number,  is  in  one 
aspect  the  truth,  rather  than  the  doctrine  of  Kant  is;  for  though  they 
are  not  mere  generalizations  and  abstractions  .from  numbered  dates 
and  durations,  places  and  extents,  they  do  exist  as  relating-principles 
which  minds  simply  put,  as  the  conditions  of  perceptive  experiences  ; 
which  by  the  nature  of  intelligence  they  must  number  in  order  to 
have  and  to  master;  while  Number  itself,  the  contrast  of  One  and 
Many,  enters  into  the  very  being  of  minds,  and  therefore  still  holds 
in  Time  and  in  Space,  which  are  the  organs,  or  media,  not  of  the  whole 
being  of  the  mind,  but  only  of  that  region  of  it  constituted  by  sensa- 
tion, —  the  material,  the  disjunct,  the  empirical.  Besides,  the  logical 
priority  of  Number  is  implied  in  the  fact  that  minds  in  putting  Time 
and  Space  a  priori  must  count  them  as  two,  since  they  discriminate 
them  with  complete  clearness,  so  that  it  is  impossible  to  work  up 
Space  out  of  Time  (as  Berkeley  and  Stuart  Mill  so  adroitly,  but  so 
vainly,  attempted  to  do),  or  Time  out  of  Space  (as  Hegel,  with  so  little 
adroitness  and  such  patent  failure,  attempted  to  do) .  No;  there  Time 
and  Space  stand,  fixed  and  inconfusable,  incapable  of  mutual  trans- 
mutation, and  thus  the  ground  of  an  abiding  difference  between  the 
inner  or  psychic  sense-world  and  the  outer  or  physical,  between  the 
subjective  and  the  (sensibly)  objective.  By  means  of  them,  the  world 
of  minds  discerns  and  bounds  securely  between  the  privacy  of  each 
and  the  publicity,  the  life  "out  of  doors,"  which  is  common  to  all; 
between  the  cohering  isolation  of  the  individual  and  the  communicat- 
ing action  of  the  society.  Indeed,  as  from  this  attained  point  of  view 
we  can  now  clearly  see,  the  real  ground  of  the  difference  between 
Time  and  Space,  and  hence  between  subjective  perception  and  the 
objective  existence  of  physical  things,  is  in  the  fact  that  a  mind,  in 
being  such,  —  in  its  very  act  of  self-definition,  —  correlates  itself 
with  a  society  of  minds,  and  so,  to  fulfill  its  nature,  in  so  far  as  this 
includes  a  world  of  experiences,  must  form  its  experience  socially  as 
well  as  privately,  and  hence  "^dll  put  forth  a  condition  of  sensuous 
communication,  as  weU  as  a  condition  of  inner  sensation.  Thus  the 
dualization  of  the  sense-world  into  inner  and  outer,  psychic  and 
physical,  subjective  and  objective,  rests  at  last  on  the  intrinsically 
social  nature  of  conscious  being;  rests  on  the  twofold  structure, 
logically  dichotomous,  of  the  self-defining  act;  and  we  get  the  explan- 
ation, from  the  nature  of  intelligence  as  such,  why  the  Sense-Forms 
are  necessarily  two,  and  only  two.  It  is  no  accident  that  we  experi- 
ence all  things  sensible  in  Time  or  in  Space,  or  in  both  together;  it  is 
the  natural  expression  of  our  primally  intelligent  being,  concerned 


188  PHILOSOPHY 

as  that  is,  directly  and  only,  with  our  self  and  its  logically  necessary 
complement,  the  other  selves;  and  so  the  natural  order,  in  its  two 
discriminated  but  complemental  portions,  the  inner  and  the  outer, 
is  founded  in  that  moral  order  which  is  given  in  the  fundamental  act  of 
our  intelligence.  It  is  this  resting  of  Space  upon  our  veritable  Objects, 
the  Other  Subjects,  that  imparts  to  it  its  externalizing  quality,  so 
that  things  in  it  are  referred  to  the  testing  of  all  minds,  not  to  ours 
only,  and  are  reckoned  external  because  measured  by  that  which  is 
alone  indeed  other  than  we. 

In  this  way  we  may  burst  the  restricting  limit  which  so  much  of 
philosophy,  and  so  much  more  of  ordinary  opinion,  has  drawn  about 
our  mental  powers  in  view  of  this  contrast  Time  and  Space,  espe- 
cially with  reference  to  the  One  and  the  Many,  and  to  the  persuasion 
that  plural  distinctions,  at  any  rate,  cannot  belong  in  the  region  of 
absolute  reality.  Ordinary  opinion  either  inclines  to  support  a  philo- 
sophy that  is  skeptical  of  either  Unity  or  Plurality  being  pertinent 
beyond  Time  and  Space,  and  thus  to  hold  by  agnosticism,  or,  if  it 
affects  affirmative  metaphysics,  tends  to  prefer  monism  to  pluralism, 
when  the  number-category  is  carried  up  into  immutable  regions:  to 
represent  the  absolutely  real  as  One,  somehow  seems  less  contradict- 
ory of  the  "fitness  of  things"  than  to  represent  it  as  Many;  more- 
over, carrying  the  Many  into  that  supreme  region,  by  implying  the 
belonging  there  of  mortals  such  as  we,  seems  shocking  to  customary 
piety,  and  full  of  extravagant  presumption.  Still,  nothing  short  of 
this  can  really  satisfy  our  deep  demand  for  a  moral  order,  a  personal 
responsibility,  nay,  an  adequate  logical  fulfillment  of  our  conception  of 
a  self  as  an  intelligence  ;  while  the  clarification  which  a  rational  plural- 
ism supplies  for  such  ingrained  puzzles  in  the  theory  of  knowledge  as 
that  of  the  source  and  finality  of  the  contrast  Time  and  Space,  to 
mention  no  others,  should  afford  a  strong  corroborative  evidence  in 
its  behalf.  And,  as  already  said,  this  view  enables  us  to  pass  the 
limit  which  Time  and  Space  are  so  often  supposed  to  put,  hopelessly, 
upon  our  concepts  of  the  ideal  grade,  the  springs  of  all  our  aspira- 
tion.   To  these,  then,  we  may  now  pass. 

We  reach  them  through  the  doorways  of  the  Necessary  vs.  the 
Contingent,  the  Unconditioned  vs.  the  Conditioned,  the  Infinite  vs.  the 
Finite,  the  Absolute  vs.  the  Relative;  and  we  recognize  them  as  our 
profoundest  foundation-concepts,  alone  deserving,  as  Kant  so  per- 
tinently said,  the  name  of  Ideas,  —  the  Soul,  the  World,  and  God. 
Associated  with  them  are  what  we  may  call  our  three  Forms  of  the 
Ideal,  —  the  True,  the  Beautiful,  the  Good.  These  Ideas  and  their 
affihated  ideals  have  the  highest  directive  and  settling  function  in 
the  organization  of  philosophy;  they  determine  its  schools  and  its 
history,  by  forming  the  centre  of  all  its  controlling  problems;  they 


FUNDAMENTAL  CONCEPTIONS   AND   METHODS     189 

prescribe  its  great  subdivisions,  breaking  it  up  into  Metaphysics, 
Esthetics,  and  Ethics,  and  Metaphysics,  again,  into  Psychology 
Cosmology,  and  Ontology,  —  or  Theology  in  the  classic  sense,  which, 
in  the  modern  sense,  becomes  the  Philosophy  of  Religion;  they  call 
into  existence,  as  essential  preparatory  and  auxiliary  disciplines. 
Logic  and  the  Theory  of  Knowledge,  or  Epistemology.  They  thus 
provide  the  true  distinctions  between  philosophy  and  the  sciences  of 
experience,  and  present  these  sciences  as  the  carrying  out,  upon 
experiential  details,  of  the  methodological  principles  which  philo- 
sophy alone  can  supply;  hence  they  lead  us  to  view  all  the  sciences 
as  in  fact  the  applied  branches,  the  completing  organs  of  philosophy, 
instead  of  its  hostile  competitors. 

As  for  the  controlling  questions  which  they  start,  these  are  such  as 
follow  :  Are  the  ideals  but  bare  ideals,  serving  only  to  cast  "a  light 
that  never  was,  on  land  or  sea?"  —  are  the  Ideas  only  bare  ideas, 
without  any  objective  being  of  their  own,  without  any  footing  in  the 
real,  serving  only  to  enhance  the  dull  facts  of  experience  with  auroral 
illusions?  The  philosophic  thinker  answers  affirmatively,  or  with 
complete  skeptical  dubiety,  or  with  a  convinced  and  uplifting  nega- 
tive, according  to  his  less  or  greater  penetration  into  the  real  meaning 
of  these  deepest  concepts,  and  depending  on  his  view  into  the  nature 
and  thought-effect  of  the  Necessary  and  the  Contingent,  the  Uncon- 
ditioned and  the  Conditioned,  the  Infinite  and  the  Finite,  the  Abso- 
lute and  the  Relative. 

And  what,  now,  are  the  accurate,  the  adequate  meanings  of  the 
three  Ideas?  —  what  does  our  profoundest  thought  intend  by  the 
Soul,  by  the  World,  by  God?  We  know  how  Kant  construed  them, 
in  consequence  of  the  course  by  which  he  came  critically  (as  he 
supposed)  upon  them,  —  as  respectively  the  paramount  Subject  of 
experiences;  the  paramount  Object  of  experiences,  or  the  Causal 
Unity  of  the  possible  series  of  sensible  objects;  and  the  complete 
Totality  of  Conditions  for  experience  and  its  objects,  itself  therefore 
the  Unconditioned.  It  is  worth  our  notice,  that  especially  by  his  con- 
struing the  idea  of  God  in  this  way,  thus  rehabilitating  the  classical 
and  scholastic  conception  of  God  as  the  Sum  of  all  Realities,  he  laid 
the  foundation  for  that  very  transfiguration  of  mysticism,  that  ideal- 
istic monism,  which  he  himself  repudiated,  but  which  his  three  noted 
successors  in  their  several  ways  so  ardently  accepted,  and  which  has 
since  so  pervaded  the  philosophic  world.  But  suppose  Kant's  alleged 
critical  analysis  of  the  three  Ideas  and  their  logical  basis  is  in  fact  far 
from  critical,  far  from  "exactly  discriminative,"  —  and  I  believe 
there  is  the  clearest  warrant  for  declaring  that  it  is,  —  then  the 
assumed  "undeniable  critical  basis"  for  idealistic  monism  will  be 
dislodged,  and  it  will  be  open  to  us  to  interpret  the  Ideas  with  accu- 
racy and  consistency  —  an  interpretation  which  may  prove  to  estab- 


190  PHILOSOPHY 

lish,  not  at  all  any  monism,  but  a  rational  pluralism.  And  this  will 
also  reveal  to  us,  I  think,  that  our  prevalent  construing  of  the  Uncon- 
ditioned and  the  Conditioned,  the  Necessary  and  the  Contingent,  the 
Infinite  and  the  Finite,  the  Absolute  and  the  Relative,  suffers  from 
an  equal  inaccuracy  of  analysis,  and  precisely  for  this  reason  gives 
a  plausible  but  in  fact  untrustworthy  support  to  the  monistic  inter- 
pretation of  God,  and  Soul,  and  World;  or,  as  Hegel  and  his  chief 
adherents  prefer  to  name  them,  God,  Mind,  and  Nature.  If  the 
Kantian  analysis  stands,  then  it  seems  to  follow,  clearly  enough,  that 
God  is  the  Inclusive  Unit  which  at  once  embraces  Mind  and  Nature, 
Soul  and  World,  expresses  itself  in  them,  and  imparts  to  them  their 
meaning;  and  the  plain  dictate  then  is,  that  Kant's  personal  pre- 
judice, and  the  personal  prejudices  of  others  like  him,  in  favor  of 
a  transcendent  God,  must  give  way  to  that  conception  of  the  Divine, 
as  immanent  and  inclusive,  which  is  alone  consistent  with  its  being 
indeed  the  Totality  of  Conditions,  —  the  Necessary  Postulate,  and 
the  Sufficient  Reason,  for  both  Subject  and  Object. 

But  will  Kant's  analysis  stand?  Have  we  not  here  another  of  his 
few  but  fatal  slips,  —  like  his  doctrine  of  the  dependence  of  Number 
upon  Time  and  Space,  and  its  consequent  subjection  to  them?  It 
surely  seems  so.  If  the  veritable  postulate  of  categorical  syllogizing 
be,  as  Kant  thinks  it  is,  merely  the  Subject,  the  self  as  experiencer  of 
presented  phenomena,  in  contrast  to  the  Object,  the  causally  united 
sum  of  possible  phenomena ;  and  if  the  true  postulate  of  conditional 
syllogizing  is  this  cosmic  Object,  as  contrasted  with  the  correlate 
Subject,  then  it  would  seem  we  cannot  avoid  certain  pertinent  ques- 
tions. Is  such  a  postulate  Subject  any  fit  and  adequate  account  of  the 
whole  Self,  of  the  Soul?  —  is  there  not  a  vital  difference  between  this 
subject-self  and  the  Self  as  Person?  —  does  not  Kant  himself  imply 
so,  in  his  doctrine  of  the  primacy  of  the  Practical  Reason?  Again:  Is 
not  the  World,  as  explained  in  Kant's  analysis,  and  as  afterwards 
made  by  him  the  solution  of  the  Cosmological  Antinomies,  simply  the 
supplemental  factor  necessarily  correlate  to  the  subjective  aspect 
of  the  conscious  life,  and  reduced  from  its  uncritical  role  of  thing-in- 
itself  to  the  intelligible  subordination  required  by  Kant's  theory  of 
Transcendental  Idealism?  —  and  can  this  be  any  adequate  account 
of  the  Idea  that  is  to  stand  in  sufficing  contrast  to  the  whole  Self, 
the  Person?  —  wiiat  less  than  the  Society  of  Persons  can  meet  the 
World-Idea  for  that?  Further:  If  with  Kant  we  take  the  World  to 
mean  no  more  than  this  object-factor  in  self-consciousness,  must  not 
the  Soul,  the  total  Self,  from  which,  according  to  Kant's  Transcen- 
dental Idealism,  both  Space  and  Time  issue,  supplying  the  basis  for 
the  immutable  contrast  between  the  experiencing  subject  and  the 
really  experienced  objects,  —  must  not  this  whole  Self  be  the  real 
meaning  of  the  "Totality  of  Conditions,  itself  unconditioned,"  which 


FUNDAMENTAL   CONCEPTIONS  AND   METHODS     191 

comes  into  view  as  simply  the  postulate  of  disjunctive  syllogizing? 
How  in  the  world  can  disjunctive  syllogizing,  the  confessed  act  of 
the  /-thinking  intelligence,  really  postulate  anything  as  Totality  of 
Conditions,  in  any  other  sense  than  the  total  of  conditions  for  such 
syllogizing?  —  namely,  the  conditioning  I  that  organizes  and  does 
the  reasoning?  There  is  surely  no  warrant  for  calling  this  total,  which 
simply  transcends  and  conditions  the  subject  and  the  object  of  sen- 
sible experiences,  by  any  loftier  name  than  that  which  Kant  had 
already  given  it  in  the  Deduction  of  the  Categories,  when  he  desig- 
nated it  the  "originally  synthetic  unity  of  apperception  (self-con- 
sciousness)," or  "  the  /-thinking  {das  ich-denke)  that  must  accompany 
all  my  mental  presentations,"  —  that  is  to  say,  the  whole  Self,  or 
thinking  Person,  idealistically  interpreted.  The  use  of  the  name  God 
in  this  connection,  where  Kant  is  in  fact  only  seeking  the  roots  of  the 
three  orders  of  the  syllogism  ivhen  reasoning  has  hy  supposition  been 
restricted  to  the  subject-matter  of  experience,  is  assuredly  without  war- 
rant; yes,  without  excuse.  In  fact,  it  is  because  Kant  sees  that  the 
third  Idea,  as  reached  through  his  analysis,  is  intrinsically  immanent, 
—  resident  in  the  self  that  syllogizes  disjunctively,  and,  because  so 
resident,  incapable  of  passing  the  bounds  of  possible  experience,  — 
while  he  also  sees  that  the  idea  of  God  should  mean  a  Being  tran- 
scendent of  every  other  thinker,  himself  a  distinct  individual  con- 
sciousness, though  not  an  empirically  limited  one,  —  it  is,  I  say, 
precisely  because  he  sees  all  this,  that  he  pronounces  the  Idea,  though 
named  with  the  name  of  God,  utterly  without  pertinence  to  indicate 
God's  existence,  and  so  enters  upon  that  part  of  his  Transcendental 
Dialectic  which  is,  in  chief,  directed  to  exposing  the  transcendental 
illusion  involved  in  the  celebrated  Ontological  Proof.  Consistently, 
Kant  in  this  famous  analytic  of  the  syllogism  should  be  talking,  not 
of  the  Soul,  the  World,  and  God,  but  of  the  Subject  (as  uniting- 
principle  of  its  sense-perceptions) ,  the  Object  (as  uniting-principle  of 
all  possible  sense-percepts),  and  the  Self  (the  whole  /  presiding  over 
experience  in  both  its  aspects,  as  these  are  discriminated  in  Time  and 
Space).  By  what  rational  title  —  even  granting  for  the  sake  of  argu- 
ment that  they  are  the  genuine  postulates  of  categorical  and  of  con- 
ditional syllogizing  —  can  this  Subject  and  this  Object,  these  corre- 
late factors  in  the  Self,  rank  as  Ideas  with  the  Idea  of  their  condi- 
tioning Whole  —  the  Self,  that  in  its  still  unaltered  identity  fulfills,  in 
Practical  Reason,  the  high  role  of  Person?  If  this  no  more  than  meets 
the  standard  of  Idea,  how  can  they  meet  it?  How  can  two  somethings, 
neither  of  which  is  the  Totality  of  Conditions,  and  both  of  which  are 
therefore  in  fact  conditioned,  deserve  the  same  title  with  that  which 
is  intrinsically  the  Totality  of  Conditions,  and,  as  such,  uncondi- 
tioned? To  call  the  conditioned  and  the  unconditioned  alike  Ideas  is 
a  confounding  of  dignities  that  Pure  Reason  should  not  tolerate, 


192  PHILOSOPHY 

whether  the  procedure  be  read  as  a  levehng  down  or  a  levehng  up. 
Distributing  the  titles  conferred  by  Pure  Reason  in  this  democratic 
fashion  reminds  us  too  much,  unhappily  for  Kant,  of  the  Cartesian 
performances  with  Substance;  whereby  God,  mind,  and  matter  be- 
came alike  "substances,"  though  only  God  could  in  truth  be  said  to 
"require  nothing  for  his  existence  save  himself,"  while  mind  and 
matter,  though  absolutely  dependent  on  God,  and  derivative  from 
him,  were  still  to  be  called  substances  in  the  "modified"  and  Pick- 
wickian sense  of  being  underived  from  each  other. 

But  if  Kant's  naming  his  third  syllogistic  postulate  the  Idea  of 
God  is  inconsequent  upon  his  analysis;  or  if,  when  the  analysis  is 
made  consequent  by  taking  the  third  Idea  to  mean  the  whole  Self, 
the  first  and  second  postulates  sink  in  conceptual  rank,  so  that  they 
cannot  with  any  pertinence  be  called  Ideas,  unless  we  are  willing  to 
keep  the  same  name  when  its  meaning  must  be  changed  in  genere,  — 
a  procedure  that  can  only  encumber  philosophy  instead  of  clearing 
its  way,  —  these  difficulties  do  not  close  the  account;  we  shall  find 
other  curious  things  in  this  noted  passage,  upon  which  part  of  the 
characteristic  outcome  of  Kant's  philosophizing  so  much  depends. 
Besides  the  misnaming  of  the  third  Idea,  we  have  already  had  to 
question,  in  view  of  the  path  by  which  he  reaches  it,  the  fitness  of 
his  calling  the  first  by  the  title  of  the  Soul;  and  likewise,  though  for 
other  and  higher  reasons,  of  his  calling  the  second  by  the  name  of  the 
World.  In  fact,  it  comes  home  to  us  that  all  of  the  Ideas  are,  in  one 
way  or  another,  misnomers;  Kant's  whole  procedure  with  them,  in 
fine,  has  already  appeared  inexact,  inconsistent,  and  therefore  uncrit^ 
ical.  But  now  we  shall  become  aware  of  certain  other  inconsistencies. 
In  coming  to  the  Subject,  as  thej  postulate  of  categorical  syllogizing, 
Kant,  you  remember,  does  so  by  the  path  of  the  relation  Subject  and 
Predicate,  arguing  that  the  chain  of  categorical  prosyllogisms  has 
for  its  limiting  concept  and  logical  motor  the  notion  of  an  absolute 
subject  that  cannot  be  a  predicate;  and  as  no  subject  of  a  judgment 
can  of  itself  give  assurance  of  fulfilling  this  condition,  he  concludes 
this  motor-limit  of  judgment-subjects  to  be  identical  with  the  Subject 
as  thinker,  upon  whom,  at  the  last,  all  judgments  depend,  and  who, 
therefore,  and  who  alone,  can  never  be  a  predicate  merely.  In  similar 
fashion,  he  finds  as  the  motor-limit  of  the  series  of  conditional 
prosyllogisms,  which  is  governed  by  the  relation  Cause  and  Effect, 
the  notion  of  an  absolute  cause  —  a  cause,  that  is,  incapable  of  being 
an  effect;  and  this,  as  undiscoverable  in  the  chain  of  phenomenal 
causes,  which  are  all  in  turn  effects,  he  concludes  is  a  pure  Idea,  the 
reason's  native  conception  of  a  necessary  linkage  among  all  changes 
in  Space,  or  of  a  Cosmic  Unity  among  physical  phenomena.  In  both 
conceptions,  then,  whether  of  the  unity  of  the  Subject  or  of  the 
World,  we  seem  to  have  a  case  of  the  unconditioned,  as  each,  surely, 


FUNDAMENTAL  CONCEPTIONS  AND   METHODS     193 

is  a  totality  of  conditions:  the  one,  for  all  possible  syllogisms  by 
Subject  and  Predicate;  the  other,  for  all  possible  syllogisms  from 
Cause  and  Effect.  Until  it  can  be  shown  that  the  syllogisms  of  the 
first  sort  and  the  syllogisms  of  the  second  are  both  conditioned  by 
the  system  of  disjunctive  syllogisms,  so  that  the  Idea  alleged  to  be  the 
totality  of  conditions  for  this  system  becomes  the  conditioning  prin- 
ciple for  both  the  others,  there  appears  to  be  no  ground  for  contrasting 
the  totality  of  conditions  presented  in  it  with  those  presented  in  the 
others,  as  if  it  were  the  absolute  Totality  of  all  Conditions,  while  the 
two  others  are  only  "relative  totalities,"  —  which  would  be  as  much 
as  to  say  they  were  only  pseudo-totalities,  both  being  conditioned 
instead  of  being  unconditioned.  But  there  seems  to  be  no  evidence, 
not  even  an  indication,  that  disjunctive  reasoning  conditions  cate- 
gorical or  conditional  —  that  it  constitutes  the  whole  kingdom,  in 
which  the  other  two  orders  of  reasoning  form  dependent  provinces, 
or  that  for  final  validation  these  must  appeal  to  the  disjunctive  series 
and  the  Idea  that  controls  it.  On  the  contrary,  any  such  relation 
seems  disproved  by  the  fact  that  the  three  types  of  syllogism  apply 
alike  in  all  subject-matter,  psychic  or  physical,  subjective  or  object- 
ive, concerning  the  Self  or  concerning  the  World,  —  yes,  concerning 
other  Selves  or  even  concerning  God;  whereas,  if  the  relation  were  a 
fact,  it  would  require  that  only  disjunctive  reasoning  can  deal  with  the' 
Unconditioned,  and  that  conditional  must  confine  itself  to  cosmic 
material,  while  categorical  pertains  only  to  the  things  of  inner  sense.. 
Such  considerations  cannot  but  shake  our  confidence  in  the  inqui- 
sition to  which  Kant  has  submitted  the  Ideas  of  Reason,  both  a& 
regards  what  they  really  mean  and  how  they  are  to  be  correlated.. 
At  all  events,  the  analysis  of  logical  procedure  and  connection  on^ 
which  his  account  of  them  is  based  is  full  of  the  confusions  and  over- 
sights  that  have  now  been  pointed  out,  and  justifies  us  in  saying 
that  his  case  is  not  established.  Hence  we  are  not  bound  to  follow- 
when  his  three  successors,  or  their  later  adherents,  proceed  in  accept- 
ance of  his  results,  and  advance  into  various  forms  of  idealism,  all  of 
the  monistic  type,  as  if  the  general  relation  between  the  three  Ideas 
had  been  demonstrably  settled  by  Kant  in  the  monist  sense,  despite 
his  not  knowing  this,  and  that  all  we  have  to  do  is  to  disregard  his- 
recorded  protests,  and  render  his  results  consistent,  and  our  idealism 
"absolute,"  by  casting  out  from  his  doctrine  the  distinction  between 
the  Theoretical  and  the  Practical  Reason,  with  the  "primacy"  of  the 
latter,  through  making  an  end  of  his  assumed  world  of  Dinge  an  sich^ 
or  "things  in  themselves."  This  movement,  I  repeat,  we  are  not 
bound  to  follow:  a  rectification  of  view  as  to  the  meaning  of  the  three 
Ideas  becomes  possible  as  soon  as  we  are  freed  from  Kant's  entangled 
method  of  discovering  and  defining  them;  and  when  this  rectification 
is  effected,  we  shall  find  that  the  question  between  monism  and 


194  PHILOSOPHY 

rational  or  harmonic  pluralism  is  at  least  open,  to  say  no  more.  Nay, 
we  are  not  to  forget  that  by  the  results  of  our  analysis  of  the  concepts 
One  and  Many,  Time  and  Space,  and  the  real  relation  between  them, 
plural  metaphysics  has  already  won  a  precedence  in  this  contest. 


THE    DEVELOPMENT   OF    PHILOSOPHY    IN    THE    NINE- 
TEENTH  CENTURY 

BY    GEORGE   TRUMBULL   LADD 

[George  Trumbull  Ladd,  Professor  of  Philosophy,  Yale  University,  b.  Jan- 
uary 19,  1842,  Painesville,  Ohio.  B.A.  Western  Reserve  College,  1864; 
B.D.  Andover  Theological  Seminary,  1869;  D.D.  Western  Reserve,  1879; 
M.A.  Yale,  1881;  LL.D.  Western  Reserve,  1895;  LL.D.  Princeton,  1896. 
Decorated  with  the  3d  Degree  of  the  Order  of  the  Rising  Sun  of  Japan, 
1899;  Pastor,  Edinburg,  Ohio,  1869-71;  ibid.,  Milwaukee,  Wis.,  1871-79; 
Professor  of  Philosophy,  Bowdoin  College,  1879-81;  ibid.,  Yale  University, 
1881 ;  Lecturer,  Harvard,  Tokio,  Bombay,  etc.,  1885 .  Member  Ameri- 
can Psychological  Association,  American  Society  of  Naturalists,  American 
Philosophical  Association,  American  Oriental  Society,  Imperial  Educational 
Society  of  Japan,  Connecticut  Academy.  Author  of  Elements  of  Physiolog- 
ical Psychology ;  Philosophy  of  Knowledge;  Philosophy  of  Mind ;  A  Theory  of 
Reality ;  and  many  other  noted  scientific  works  and  papers.] 

The  histor}'-  of  man's  critical  and  reflective  thought  upon  the 
more  ultimate  problems  of  nature  and  of  his  own  life  has,  indeed, 
its  period  of  quickened  progress,  relative  stagnation,  and  apparent 
decline.  Great  thinkers  are  born  and  die,  "schools  of  philosophy," 
so-called,  arise,  flourish,  and  become  discredited;  and  tendencies 
of  various  characteristics  mark  the  national  or  more  general  Zeit- 
geist of  the  particular  centuries.  And  always,  a  certain  deep  under- 
current, or  powerful  stream  of  the  rational  evolution  of  humanity, 
flows  silently  onward.  But  these  periods  of  philosophical  develop- 
ment do  not  correspond  to  those  which  have  been  marked  off  for 
man  by  the  rhythmic  motion  of  the  heavenly  bodies,  or  by  himself 
for  purposes  of  greater  convenience  in  practical  affairs.  The  pro- 
posal, therefore,  to  treat  any  century  of  philosophical  development 
as  though  it  could  be  taken  out  of,  and  considered  apart  from,  this 
constant  unfolding  of  man's  rational  life  is,  of  necessity,  doomed  to 
failure.  And,  indeed,  the  nineteenth  century  is  no  exception  to  the 
general  truth. 

There  is,  however,  one  important  and  historical  fact  which  makes 
more  definite,  and  more  feasible,  the  attempt  to  present  in  outline 
the  history  of  the  philosophical  development  of  the  nineteenth 
century.  This  fact  is  the  death  of  Immanuel  Kant,  February  12, 
1804.     In  a  very  unusual  way  this  event  marks  the  close  of  the 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    195 

development  of  philosophy  in  the  eighteenth  century.  In  a  yet 
more  unusual  way  the  same  event  defines  the  beginning  of  the  philo- 
sophical development  of  the  nineteenth  century.  The  proposal  is, 
therefore,  not  artificial,  but  in  accordance  with  the  truth  of  history, 
if  we  consider  the  problems,  movements,  results,  and  present  con- 
dition of  this  development,  so  far  as  the  fulfillment  of  our  general 
purpose  is  concerned,  in  the  light  of  the  critical  philosophy  of  Kant. 
This  purpose  may  then  be  further  defined  in  the  following  way :  to 
trace  the  history  of  the  evolution  of  critical  and  reflective  thought 
over  the  more  ultimate  problems  of  Nature  and  of  human  life,  in 
the  Western  World  during  the  last  hundred  years,  and  from  the 
standpoint  of  the  conclusions,  both  negative  and  positive,  which 
are  best  embodied  in  the  works  of  the  philosopher  of  Konigsberg. 
This  purpose  we  shall  try  to  fulfill  in  these  four  divisions  of  our  theme : 
(1)  A  statement  of  the  problems  of  philosophy  as  they  were  given  over 
to  the  nineteenth  century  by  the  Kantian  Critique;  (2)  a  brief 
description  of  the  lines  of  movement  along  which  the  attempts  at 
the  improved  solution  of  these  problems  have  proceeded,  and  of  the 
principal  influences  contributing  to  these  attempts;  (3)  a  sum- 
mary of  the  principal  results  of  these  movements  —  the  items,  so  to 
say,  of  progress  in  philosophy  which  may  be  credited  to  the  last  cen- 
tury; and  finally,  (4)  a  survey  of  the  present  state  of  these  pro- 
blems as  they  are  now  to  be  handed  down  by  the  nineteenth  to  the 
twentieth  century.  Truly  an  immensely  difficult,  if  not  an  impos- 
sible task,  is  involved  in  this  purpose! 

I.  The  problems  which  the  critical  philosophy  undertook  defini- 
tively to  solve  may  be  divided  into  three  classes.  The  first  is  the 
epistemological  problem,  or  the  problem  offered  by  human  know- 
ledge —  its  essential  nature,  its  fixed  limitations,  if  such  there  be, 
and  its  ontological  validity.  It  was  this  problem  which  Kant  brought 
to  the  front  in  such  a  manner  that  certain  subsequent  writers  on 
philosophy  have  claimed  it  to  be,  not  only  the  primary  and  most 
important  branch  of  philosophical  discipline,  but  to  comprise  the 
sum-total  of  what  human  reflection  and  critical  thought  can  suc- 
cessfully compass.  "We  call  philosophy  self-knowledge,"  says  one 
of  these  writers.  "  The  theory  of  knowledge  is  the  true  prima  philo- 
sophia,"  says  another.  Kant  himself  regarded  it  as  the  most  im- 
perative demand  of  reason  to  establish  a  science  that  shall  "deter- 
mine a  priori  the  possibility,  the  principles,  and  the  extent  of  all 
cognitions."  The  burden  of  the  epistemological  problem  has  pressed 
heavily  upon  the  thought  of  the  nineteenth  century;  the  different 
attitudes  toward  this  problem,  and  its  different  alleged  solutions, 
have  been  most  influential  factors  in  determining  the  philosophical 
discussions,  divisions,  schools,  and  permanent  or  transitory  achieve- 
ments of  the  centurv. 


196  PHILOSOPHY 

In  the  epistemological  problem  as  offered  by  the  Kantian  philo- 
sophy of  cognition  there  is  involved  the  subordinate  but  highly 
important  question  as  to  the  proper  method  of  philosophy.  Is  the 
method  of  criticism,  as  that  method  was  employed  in  the  three 
Critiques  of  Kant,  the  exclusive,  the  sole  appropriate  and  product- 
ive way  of  advancing  human  philosophical  thought?  I  do  not 
think  that  the  experience  of  the  nineteenth  century  warrants  an 
affirmative  answer  to  this  question  of  method.  This  experience  has 
certainly,  however,  resulted  in  demonstrating  the  need  of  a  more 
thorough,  consistent,  and  fundamental  use  of  the  critical  method 
than  that  in  which  it  was  employed  by  Kant.  And  this  improved  use 
of  the  critical  method  has  induced  a  more  profound  study  of  the 
psychology  of  cognition,  and  of  the  historical  development  of  philo- 
sophy in  the  branch  of  epistemology.  More  especially,  however,  it 
has  led  to  the  reinstatement  of  the  value-judgments,  as  means  of 
cognition,  in  their  right  relations  of  harmony  with  the  judgments 
of  fact  and  of  law. 

The  second  of  the  greater  problems  which  the  critical  philosophy 
of  the  eighteenth  handed  on  to  the  nineteenth  century  is  the  onto- 
logical  problem.  This  problem,  even  far  more  than  the  epistemo- 
logical, has  excited  the  intensest  interest,  and  called  for  the  pro- 
foundest  thought,  of  reflective  minds  during  the  last  hundred  years. 
This  problem  engages  in  the  inquiry  as  to  what  Reality  is;  for  to 
define  philosophy  from  the  ontological  point  of  view  renders  it 
"the  rational  science  of  reality;"  or,  at  least,  "the  science  of  the 
supreme  and  most  important  realities."  In  spite  of  the  fact  that 
the  period  immediately  following  the  conclusion  of  the  Kantian 
criticism  was  the  age  when  the  people  were  singing 

"Da  die  Metaphysik  vor  Kurzem  unheerbt  dbging, 
Werden  die  Dinge  an  sich  jetzo  suh  hasta  verkauft," 

the  cultivation  of  the  ontological  problem,  and  the  growth  of  sys- 
tematic metaphysics  in  the  nineteenth  century,  had  never  pre- 
viously been  surpassed.  In  spite  of,  or  rather  because  of,  the  fact 
that  Kant  left  the  ancient  body  of  metaphysics  so  dismembered  and 
discredited,  and  his  otvti  ontological  structure  in  such  hopeless  con- 
fusion, all  the  several  buildings  both  of  Idealism  and  of  Realism 
either  rose  quickly  or  were  erected  upon  the  foundations  made  bare 
by  the  critical  philosophy. 

But  especially  unsatisfactory  to  the  thought  of  the  first  quarter 
of  the  nineteenth  century  was  the  Kantian  position  with  reference 
to  the  problem  in  which,  after  all,  both  the  few  who  cultivate  philo- 
sophy and  the  multitude  who  share  in  its  fruits  are  always  most 
truly  interested;  and  this  is  the  ethico-religious  problem.  In  the 
judgment  of  the  generation  which  followed  him,  Kant  had  achieved 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY    197 

for  those  who  accepted  his  points  of  view,  his  method  of  philo- 
sophizing, and  his  results,  much  greater  success  in  "removing  know- 
ledge" than  in  "finding  room  for  faith."  For  he  seemed  to  have 
left  the  positive  truths  of  Ethics  so  involved  in  the  negative  posi- 
tions of  his  critique  of  knowledge  as  greatly  to  endanger  them;  and 
to  have  entangled  the  conceptions  of  religion  with  those  of  morality 
in  a  manner  to  throw  doubt  upon  them  both. 

The  breach  between  the  human  cognitive  faculties  and  the  onto- 
logical  doctrines  and  conceptions  on  which  morality  and  religion 
had  been  supposed  to  rest  firmly,  the  elaborately  argued  distrust 
and  skepticism  which  had  been  aimed  against  the  ability  of  human 
reason  to  reach  reality,  and  the  consequent  danger  which  threatened 
the  most  precious  judgments  of  worth  and  the  ontological  value 
of  ethical  and  sesthetical  sentiments,  could  not  remain  unnoticed, 
or  fail  to  promote  ceaseless  and  earnest  efforts  to  heal  it.  The  hitherto 
accepted  solutions  of  the  problems  of  cognition,  of  being,  and  of 
man's  ethico-religious  experience,  could  not  survive  the  critical 
philosophy.  But  the  solutions  which  the  critical  philosophy  itself 
offered  could  not  fail  to  excite  opposition  and  to  stimulate  further 
criticism.  Moreover,  certain  factors  in  human  nature,  certain  inter- 
ests in  human  social  life,  and  certain  needs  of  humanity,  not  fully 
recognized  and  indeed  scarcely  noticed  by  criticism,  could  not 
fail  to  revive  and  to  enforce  their  ancient,  perennial,  and  valid 
claims. 

In  a  word,  Kant  left  the  main  problems  of  philosophy  involved 
in  numerous  contradictions.  The  result  of  his  penetrating  but  ex- 
cessive analysis  was  unwarrantably  to  contrast  sense  with  under- 
standing; to  divide  reason  as  constitutive  from  reason  as  regulative; 
to  divorce  the  moral  law  from  our  concrete  experience  of  the  results 
of  good  and  bad  conduct,  true  morality  from  many  of  the  noblest 
desires  and  sentiments,  and  to  set  in  opposition  phenomena  and 
noumena,  order  and  freedom,  knowledge  and  faith,  science  and 
religion.  Now  the  highest  aim  of  philosophy  is  reconciliation.  What 
wonder,  then,  that  the  beginning  of  the  last  century  felt  the  stimu- 
lus of  the  unreconciled  condition  of  the  problems  of  philosophy  at 
the  end  of  the  preceding  century!  The  greatest,  most  stimulating 
inheritance  of  the  philosophy  of  the  nineteenth  century  from  the 
philosophy  of  the  eighteenth  century  was  the  "post-Kantian  pro- 
blems." 

11.  The  lines  of  the  movement  of  philosophical  thought  and  the 
principal  contributory  influences  which  belong  to  the  nineteenth 
century  may  be  roughly  divided  into  two  classes;  namely,  (1) 
those  which  tended  in  the  direction  of  carrying  to  the  utmost  ex- 
treme the  negative  and  destructive  criticism  of  Kant,  and  (2)  those 
which,   either  mainly  favoring  or  mainly   antagonizing  the   con- 


198  PHILOSOPHY 

elusions  of  the  Kantian  criticism,  endeavored  to  place  the  positive 
answer  to  all  three  of  these  great  problems  of  philosophy  upon 
more  comprehensive,  scientifically  defensible,  and  permanently 
sure  foundations.  The  one  class  so  far  completed  the  attempt  to 
remove  the  knowledge  at  which  philosophy  aims  as,  by  the  end  of 
the  first  half  of  the  century,  to  have  left  no  rational  ground  for 
any  kind  of  faith.  The  other  class  had  not,  even  by  the  end  of  the 
second  half  of  the  century,  as  yet  agreed  upon  any  one  scheme  for 
harmonizing  the  various  theories  of  knowledge,  of  reality,  and  of 
the  ground  of  morality  and  religion.  There  appeared,  however,  — 
especially  during  the  last  two  decades  of  the  century,  —  certain 
signs  of  convergence  upon  positions,  to  occupy  which  is  favorable 
for  agreement  upon  such  a  scheme,  and  which  now  promise  a  new 
constructive  era  for  philosophy.  The  terminus  of  the  destructive 
movement  has  been  reached  in  our  present-day  positivism  and  philo- 
sophical skepticism.  For  this  movement  there  would  appear  to  be 
no  more  beyond  in  the  same  direction.  The  terminus  of  the  other 
movement  can  only  be  somewhat  dimly  descried.  It  may  perhaps 
be  predicted  with  a  reasonable  degree  of  confidence  as  some  form 
of  ontological  Idealism  (if  we  may  use  such  a  phrase)  that  shall  be 
at  once  more  thoroughly  grounded  in  man's  total  experience,  as 
interpreted  by  modern  science,  and  also  more  satisfactory  to  human 
ethical,  sesthetical,  and  religious  ideals,  than  any  form  of  system- 
atic philosophy  has  hitherto  been.  But  to  say  even  this  much  is 
perhaps  unduly  to  anticipate. 

If  we  attempt  to  fathom  and  estimate  the  force  of  the  various 
streams  of  influence  which  have  shaped  the  history  of  the  philo- 
sophical development  of  the  nineteenth  century,  I  think  there  can 
be  no  doubt  that  the  profoundest  and  the  most  powerful  is  the  one 
influence  which  must  be  recognized  and  reckoned  with  in  all  the 
centuries.  This  influence  is  humanity's  undying  interest  in  its 
moral,  civil,  and  religious  ideals,  and  in  the  civil  and  religious  in- 
stitutions which  give  a  faithful  but  temporary  expression  to  these 
ideals.  In  the  long  run,  every  fragmentary  or  systematic  attempt 
at  the  solution  of  the  problem  of  philosophy  must  sustain  the  test 
of  an  ability  to  contribute  something  of  value  to  the  realization  of 
these  ideals.  The  test  which  the  past  century  has  proposed  for  its 
own  thinkers,  and  for  its  various  schools  of  philosophy,  is  by  far  the 
severest  which  has  ever  been  proposed.  For  the  most  part  unosten- 
tatiously and  in  large  measure  silently,  the  thoughtful  few  and 
the  comparatively  thoughtless  multitude  have  been  contributing, 
either  destructively  or  constructively,  to  the  effort  at  satisfaction 
for  the  rising  spiritual  life  of  man.  And  if  in  some  vague  but 
impressive  manner  we  speak  of  this  thirst  for  spiritual  satisfac- 
tion as  characteristic  of  any  period  of  human  history,  we  may  say, 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    199 

I  believe,  that  it  has  been  peculiarly  characteristic  and  especially 
powerful  as  an  influence  during  the  last  hundred  years.  The  opin- 
ions, sentiments,  and  ideals  which  shape  the  development  of  the 
institutions  of  the  church  and  state,  and  the  freer  activities  of  the 
same  opinions,  sentiments,  and  ideals,  have  been  in  this  century, 
as  they  have  been  in  every  century,  the  principal  factors  in  deter- 
mining the  character  of  its  philosophical  development. 

But  a  more  definite  and  visible  kind  of  influence  has  constantly 
proceeded  from  the  centres  of  the  higher  education.  The  univers- 
ities —  especially  of  Germany,  next,  perhaps  of  Scotland,  but 
also  of  England  and  the  United  States,  and  even  in  less  degree  of 
France  and  Italy  —  have  both  fostered  and  shaped  the  evolution 
of  critical  and  reflective  thought,  and  of  its  product  as  philosophy. 
In  Germany  during  the  eighteenth  century  the  greater  universities 
had  been  emancipating  themselves  from  the  stricter  forms  of  polit- 
ical and  court  favoritism  and  of  ecclesiastical  protection  and  con- 
trol. This  emancipation  had  already  operated  at  the  beginning  of 
the  nineteenth  century,  and  it  continued  more  and  more  to  operate 
throughout  this  century,  for  participation  in  that  free  thought 
whose  spirit  is  absolutely  essential  to  the  flourishing  of  true  philo- 
sophy. All  the  other  colleges  and  universities  can  scarcely  repay 
the  debt  which  modern  philosophy  owes  to  the  universities  of  Ger- 
many. The  institutions  of  the  higher  education  which  are  moulded 
after  this  spirit,  and  which  have  a  generous  share  of  this  spirit, 
have  everywhere  been  schools  of  thought  as  weU  as  schools  of  learn- 
ing and  research.  Without  the  increasing  numbers  and  growing 
encouragement  of  such  centres  for  the  cultivation  of  the  discipline 
of  critical  and  reflective  thinking,  it  is  difficult  to  conjecture  how 
much  the  philosophical  development  of  the  nineteenth  century  would 
have  lost.  Lihertas  docendi  and  Academische  Freiheit  —  without  these 
philosophy  has  one  of  its  wings  fatally  wounded  or  severely  clipped. 

Not  all  the  philosophy  of  the  last  century,  however,  was  born 
and  developed  in  academical  centres  and  under  academical  in- 
fluences. In  Germany,  Great  Britain,  and  France,  the  various 
so-caUed  "Academies"  or  other  unacademical  associations  of  men 
of  scientific  interests  and  attainments  —  notably,  the  Berlin  Acad- 
emy, which  has  been  called  "the  seat  of  an  anti-scholastic  popular 
philosophy"  —  were  during  the  first  half  of  the  nineteenth  century 
contributing  by  their  conspicuous  failures  as  well  as  by  their  less 
conspicuous  successes,  important  factors  to  the  constructive  new 
thought  of  the  latter  half  of  the  nineteenth  century.  In  general, 
although  these  men  decried  system  and  were  themselves  inade- 
quately prepared  to  treat  the  problems  of  philosophy,  whether 
from  the  historical  or  the  speculative  and  critical  point  of  view,  they 
cannot  be  wholly  neglected  in  estimating  its  development.    Clever 


200  PHILOSOPHY 

reasoning,  and  witty  and  epigrammatic  writing  on  scientific  or 
other  allied  subjects,  cannot  indeed  be  called  philosophy  in  the 
stricter  meaning  of  the  word.  But  this  so-called  "popular  philo- 
sophy "  has  greatly  helped  in  a  way  to  free  thought  from  its  too  close 
bondage  to  scholastic  tradition.  And  even  the  despite  of  philosophy, 
and  sneering  references  to  its  "barrenness,"  which  formerly  charac- 
terized the  meetings  and  the  writings  of  this  class  of  its  critics,  but 
which  now  are  happily  much  less  frequent,  have  been  on  the  whole 
both  a  valuable  check  and  a  stimulus  to  her  devotees.  He  would  be 
too  narrow  and  sour  a  disciple  of  scholastic  metaphysics  and  sys- 
tematic philosophy,  who,  because  of  the  levity  or  scorning  of  "out- 
siders," should  refuse  them  all  credit.  Indeed,  the  lesson  of  the  close 
of  the  nineteenth  century  may  well  enough  be  the  motto  for  the 
beginning  of  the  twentieth  century :  In  philosophy  —  since  to  philo- 
sophize is  natural  and  inevitable  for  all  rational  beings  —  there  really 
are  no  outsiders. 

In  this  connection  it  is  most  interesting  to  notice  how  men  of  the 
type  just  referred  to,  were  at  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century 
found,  grouped  around  such  thinkers  as  Mendelssohn,  Lessing, 
F.  Nicolai,  —  representing  a  somewhat  decided  reaction  from  the 
French  realism  to  the  German  idealism.  The  work  of  the  Academ- 
icians in  the  criticism  of  Kant  was  carried  forward  by  Jacobi, 
who,  at  the  time  of  his  death,  was  the  pensioned  president  of  the 
Academy  at  Munich.  Some  of  these  same  critics  of  the  Kantian 
philosophy  showed  a  rather  decided  preference  for  the  "common- 
sense"  philosophy  of  the  Scottish  School. 

But  both  inside  and  outside  of  the  Universities  and  Academies 
the  scientific  spirit  and  acquisitions  of  the  nineteenth  century  have 
most  profoundly,  and  on  the  whole  favorably,  affected  the  develop- 
ment of  its  philosophy.  In  the  wider  meaning  of  the  word,  "  science, " 
—  the  meaning,  namely,  in  which  BoiencQ^Wissenschajt, — philo- 
sophy aims  to  be  scientific;  and  science  can  never  be  indifferent 
to  philosophy.  In  their  common  aim  at  a  rational  and  unitary  sys- 
tem of  principles,  which  shall  explain  and  give  its  due  significance  to 
the  totality  of  human  experience,  science  and  philosophy  can  never 
remain  long  in  antagonism;  they  ought  never  even  temporarily  to 
be  divided  in  interests,  or  in  the  spirit  which  leads  each  generously 
to  recognize  the  importance  of  the  other.  The  early  part  of  the  last 
century  was,  indeed,  too  much  under  the  influence  of  that  almost 
exclusively  speculative  Natur-philosophie,  of  which  Schelling  and 
Hegel  were  the  most  prominent  exponents.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
conception  of  nature  as  a  vast  interconnected  and  unitar}^  system 
of  a  rational  order,  unfolding  itself  in  accordance  with  teleological 
principles,  —  however  manifold  and  obscure,  —  is  a  noble  concep- 
tion and  not  destined  to  pass  away. 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE    NINETEENTH   CENTURY    201 

On  the  continent  —  at  least  in  France,  where  it  had  attained 
its  highest  development  —  the  scientific  spirit  was,  at  the  close 
of  the  eighteenth  century,  on  the  whole  opposed  to  systematization. 
The  impulse  to  both  science  and  philosophy  during  both  the  eight- 
eenth and  the  nineteenth  centuries,  over  the  entire  continent  of 
Europe,  was  chiefly  due  to  the  epoch-making  work  of  that  greatest 
of  all  titles  in  the  modern  scientific  development  of  the  Western 
World,  the  Principia  of  Newton.  In  mathematics  and  the  phys- 
ical sciences,  during  the  early  third  or  half  of  the  last  century,  Great 
Britain  also  has  a  roll  of  distinguished  names  which  compares  most 
favorably  with  that  of  either  France  or  Germany.  But  in  England, 
France,  and  the  United  States,  during  the  whole  century,  science  has 
lacked  the  breadth  and  philosophic  spirit  which  it  had  in  Germany 
during  the  first  three  quarters  of  this  period.  During  all  that  time 
the  German  man  of  science  was,  as  a  rule,  a  scholar,  an  investi- 
gator, a  teacher,  and  a  philosopher.  Science  and  philosophy  thrived 
better,  however,  in  Scotland  than  elsewhere  outside  of  Germany,  so 
far  as  their  relations  in  interdependence  were  concerned.  Into  the 
Scottish  universities  Playfair  introduced  some  of  the  continental 
suggestions  toward  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century,  so  that  there 
was  less  of  exclusiveness  and  unfriendly  rivalry  between  science  and 
philosophy;  and  both  profited  thereby.  In  the  United  States,  during 
the  first  half  or  more  of  the  century,  so  dominant  were  the  theo- 
logical and  practical  interests  and  influences  that  there  was  little 
free  development  of  either  science  or  philosophy,  —  if  we  interpret 
the  one  as  the  equivalent  of  Wissenschaft  and  understand  the  other 
in  the  stricter  meaning  of  the  word. 

The  history  of  the  development  of  the  scientific  spirit  and  of  the 
achievements  of  the  particular  sciences  is  not  the  theme  of  this 
paper.  To  trace  in  detail,  or  even  in  its  large  outlines,  the  reciprocal 
influence  of  science  and  philosophy  during  the  past  hundred  years, 
would  itself  require  far  more  than  the  space  allotted  to  me.  It  must 
suffice  to  say  that  the  various  advances  in  the  efforts  of  the  par- 
ticular sciences  to  enlarge  and  to  define  the  conceptions  and  prin- 
ciples employed  to  portray  the  Being  of  the  World  in  its  totality, 
have  somewhat  steadily  grown  more  and  more  completely  meta- 
physical, and  more  and  more  of  positive  importance  for  the  recon- 
struction of  systematic  philosophy.  The  latter  has  not  simply  been 
disciplined  by  science,  compelled  to  improve  its  method,  and  to  ex- 
amine all  its  previous  claims.  But  philosophy  has  also  been  greatly 
enriched  by  science  with  respect  to  its  material  awaiting  synthesis, 
and  it  has  been  not  a  little  profited  by  the  unsuccessful  attempts  of 
the  current  scientific  theories  to  give  themselves  a  truly  satisfactory 
account  of  that  Ultimate  Reality  which,  to  understand  the  better, 
is  no  unworthy  aim  of  their  combined  efforts. 


202  ■       PHILOSOPHY 

During  the  nineteenth  century  science  has  seen  many  important 
additions  to  that  Ideal  of  Nature  and  her  processes,  to  form  which 
in  a  unitary  and  harmonizing  but  comprehensive  way  is  the  philo- 
sophical goal  of  science.  The  gross  mechanical  conception  of  nature 
which  prevailed  in  the  earlier  part  of  the  eighteenth  century  has  long 
since  been  abandoned,  as  quite  inadequate  to  our  experience  with 
her  facts,  forces,  and  laws.  The  kinetic  view,  which  began  with 
Huygens,  Euler,  and  Ampere,  and  which  was  so  amplified  by  Lord 
Kelvin  and  Clerk-Maxwell  in  England,  and  by  Helmholtz  and  others 
in  Germany,  on  account  of  its  success  in  explaining  the  phenomena 
of  light,  of  gases,  etc.,  very  naturally  led  to  the  attempt  to  develop 
a  kinetic  theory,  a  doctrine  of  energetics,  which  should  explain  all 
phenomena.  But  the  conception  of  "that  which  moves,"  the  ex- 
perience of  important  and  persistent  qualitative  differentiae,  and 
the  need  of  assuming  ends  and  purposes  served  by  the  movement, 
are  troublesome  obstacles  in  the  way  of  giving  such  a  completeness 
to  this  theory  of  the  Being  of  the  World.  Yet  again  the  amazing 
success  which  the  theory  of  evolution  has  shown  in  explaining  the 
phenomena  with  which  the  various  biological  sciences  concern 
themselves,  has  lent  favor  during  the  latter  half  of  the  century  to 
the  vitalistic  and  genetic  view  of  nature.  For  all  our  most  elaborate 
and  advanced  kinetic  theories  seem  utterly  to  fail  us  as  explanatory 
when  we,  through  the  higher  powers  of  the  microscope,  stand  won- 
dering and  face  to  face  with  the  evolution  of  a  single  living  cell. 
But  from  such  a  view  of  the  essential  Being  of  the  World  as  evolu- 
tion suggests  to  the  psycho-physical  theory  of  nature  is  not  an 
impassable  gulf.  And  thus,  under  its  growing  wealth  of  knowledge, 
science  may  be  leading  up  to  an  Ideal  of  the  Ultimate  Reality,  in 
which  philosophy  will  gratefully  and  gladly  coincide.  At  any  rate, 
the  modern  conception  of  nature  and  the  modern  conception  of 
God  are  not  so  far  apart  from  each  other,  as  either  of  these  con- 
ceptions is  now  removed  from  the  conceptions  covered  by  the  same 
terms,  some  centuries  gone  by. 

There  is  one  of  the  positive  sciences,  however,  with  which  the 
development  of  philosophy  during  the  last  century  has  been  par- 
ticularly allied.  This  science  is  ps^^chology.  To  speak  of  its  history 
is  not  the  theme  of  this  paper.  But  it  should  be  noted  in  passing 
how  the  development  of  psychology  has  brought  into  connection 
with  the  physical  and  biological  sciences  the  development  of  philo- 
sophy. This  union,  whether  it  be  for  better  or  for  worse,  —  and, 
on  the  whole,  I  believe  it  to  be  for  better  rather  than  for  worse,  — 
has  been  in  a  very  special  way  the  result  of  the  last  century.  In 
tracing  its  details  we  should  have  to  speak  of  the  dependence  of 
certain  branches  of  psychology  on  physiology,  and  upon  Sir  Charles 
Bell's  discovery  of  the  difference  between  the  sensory  and  the  motor 


PHILOSOPHY  IN   THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY    203 

nerves.  This  discovery  was  the  contribution  of  the  beginning  of 
the  century  to  an  entire  line  of  discoveries,  which  have  ended  at  the 
close  of  the  century  with  putting  the  localization  of  cerebral  func- 
tion upon  a  firm  experimental  basis.  Of  scarcely  less  importance 
has  been  the  cellular  theory  as  applied  (1838)  by  Matthias  Schleiden, 
a  pupil  of  Fries  in  philosophy,  to  plants,  and  by  Theodor  Schwann 
about  the  same  time  to  animal  organisms.  To  these  must  be  added 
the  researches  of  Johannes  Miiller  (1801-1858),  the  great  biologist, 
a  hstener  to  Hegel's  lectures,  whose  law  of  specific  energies  brings 
him  into  connection  with  psychology  and,  through  psychology,  to 
philosophy.  Even  more  true  is  this  of  Helmholtz,  whose  Lehre  von 
den  Tonempfindungen  (1862)  and  Physiologische  Optik  (1867)  placed 
him  in  even  closer,  though  still  mediate,  relations  to  philosophy. 
But  perhaps  especially  Gustav  Theodor  Fechner  (1801-1887),  whose 
researches  in  psycho-physics  laid  the  foundations  of  whatever,  either 
as  psychology  or  as  philosophy,  goes  under  this  name;  and  whether 
the  doctrine  have  reference  to  the  relation  of  man's  mind  and  body, 
or  to  the  wider  relations  of  spirit  and  matter. 

In  my  judgment  it  cannot  be  affirmed  that  the  attempts  of  the 
latter  half  of  the  nineteenth  century  to  develop  an  experimental 
science  of  psychology  in  independence  of  philosophical  criticism  and 
metaphysical  assumption,  or  the  claims  of  this  science  to  have 
thrown  any  wholly  new  light  upon  the  statement,  or  upon  the 
solution  of  philosophical  problems,  have  been  largely  successful. 
But  certain  more  definitely  psychological  questions  have  been  to 
a  commendable  degree  better  analyzed  and  elucidated;  the  new 
experimental  methods,  where  confined  within  their  legitimate 
sphere,  have  been  amply  justified;  and  certain  gMas?!-metaphysical 
views  respecting  the  nature  of  the  human  mind,  and  even,  if  you 
will,  the  nature  of  the  Spirit  in  general  —  have  been  placed  in  a 
more  favorable  and  scientifically  engaging  attitude  toward  speculat- 
ive philosophy.  This  seems  to  me  to  be  especially  true  with  respect 
to  two  problems  in  which  both  empirical  psychology  and  philosophy 
have  a  common  and  profound  interest.  These  are  (1)  the  complex 
synthesis  of  mental  functions  involved  in  every  act  of  true  cogni- 
tion, together  with  the  bearing  which  the  psychology  of  cognition 
has  upon  epistemological  problems;  and  (2)  the  yet  more  complex 
and  profound  analysis,  from  the  psychological  point  of  view,  of  what 
it  is  to  be  a  self-conscious  and  self-determining  Will,  a  true  Self, 
together  with  the  bearing  which  the  psychology  of  selfhood  has 
upon  all  the  problems  "of  ethics,  aesthetics,  and  religion. 

The  more  obvious  and  easily  traceable  influences  which  have 
operated  to  incite  and  direct  the  philosophical  development  of  the 
nineteenth  century  are,  of  course,  dependent  upon  the  teachings  and 
writings  of  philosophers,  and  the  schools  of  philosophy  which  they 


204  PHILOSOPHY 

have  founded.  To  speak  of  these  influences  even  in  outhne  would  be 
to  write  a  manual  of  the  history  of  philosophy  during  that  hundred  of 
years,  which  has  been  of  all  others  by  far  the  most  fruitful  in  material 
results,  whatever  estimate  may  be  put  upon  the  separate  or  combined 
values  of  the  individual  thinkers  and  their  so-called  schools.  No 
fewer  than  seven  or  eight  relatively  independent  or  partially  antag- 
onistic movements,  which  may  be  traced  back  either  directly  or 
more  indirectly  to  the  critical  philosophy,  and  to  the  form  in  which 
the  problems  of  philosophy  were  left  by  Kant,  sprung  up  during  the 
century.  In  Germany  chiefly,  there  arose  the  Faith-philosophy,  the 
Romantic  School,  and  Rational  Idealism;  in  France,  Eclecticism  and 
Positivism  (if,  indeed,  the  latter  can  be  called  a  philosophy) ;  in  Scot- 
land, a  naive  and  crude  form  of  Realism,  which  served  well  for  the 
time  as  an  antagonist  of  a  skeptical  idealism,  but  which  itself  con- 
tributed to  an  improved  form  of  Idealism;  and  in  the  United  States, 
or  rather  in  New  England,  a  peculiar  kind  of  Transcendentalism  of 
the  sentimental  type.  But  all  these  movements  of  thought,  and 
others  lying  somewhere  midway  between,  in  a  pair  composed  of  any 
two,  together  with  a  steadfast  remainder  of  almost  every  sort  of 
Dogmatism,  and  all  degrees  and  kinds  of  Skepticism,  have  been  inter- 
mixed and  contending  with  one  another,  in  all  these  countries.  Such 
has  been  the  varied,  undefinable,  and  yet  intensely  stimulating  and 
interesting  character  of  the  development  of  systematic  and  scholastic 
philosophy,  during  the  nineteenth  century. 

The  early  opposition  to  Kant  in  Germany  was,  in  the  main,  two- 
fold :  —  both  to  his  peculiar  extreme  analysis  with  its  philosophical 
conclusions,  and  also  to  all  systematic  as  distinguished  from  a  more 
popular  and  literary  form  of  philosophizing.  Toward  the  close  of  the 
eighteenth  century  a  group  of  men  had  been  writing  upon  philo- 
sophical questions  in  a  spirit  and  method  quite  foreign  to  that  held 
in  respect  by  the  critical  philosophy.  It  is  not  wholly  without  signi- 
ficance that  Lessing,  whose  aim  had  been  to  use  common  sense  and 
literary  skill  in  clearing  up  obscure  ideas  and  improving  and  illumin- 
ing the  life  of  man,  died  in  the  very  year  of  the  appearance  of  Kant's 
Kritik  der  reineyi  Vernunft.  Of  this  class  of  men  an  historian  dealing 
with  this  period  has  said,  "  There  is  hardly  one  who  does  not  quote 
somewhere  or  other  Pope's  saying,  'The  proper  study  of  mankind 
is  man.'"  To  this  class  belong  Hamann  (1730-1788),  the  inspirer 
of  Herder  and  Jacobi.  The  former,  who  was  essentially  a  poet  and 
a  friend  of  Goethe,  controverted  Kant  with  regard  to  his  doctrine  of 
reason,  his  antithesis  between  the  individual  and  the  race,  and  his 
schism  between  things  as  empirically  known  and  the  known  unity  in 
the  Ground  of  their  being  and  becoming.  Herder's  path  to  truth  was 
highly  colored  with  flowers  of  rhetoric ;  but  the  promise  was  that  he 
would  lead  men  back  to  the  heavenly  city.    Jacobi,  too,  with  due 


PHILOSOPHY  IN   THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY     205 

aUowance  made  for  the  injury  wrought  by  his  divorce  of  the  two 
philosophies,  —  that  of  faith  and  that  of  science,  —  and  his  excessive 
estimate  of  the  value-judgments  which  repose  in  the  mist  of  a  feeling- 
faith,  added  something  of  worth  by  way  of  exposing  the  barrenness 
of  the  Kantian  doctrine  of  an  unknowable  "Thing-in-itself." 

From  men  like  Fr.  Schlegel  (1772-1829),  whose  valid  protest  against 
the  sharp  separation  of  speculative  philosophy  from  the  sesthetical, 
social,  and  ethical  life,  assumed  the  "standpoint  of  irony,"  little  real 
result  in  the  discovery  of  truth  could  be  expected.  But  Schleier- 
macher  (1768-1834),  in  spite  of  that  mixture  of  unfused  elements 
which  has  made  his  philosophy  "  a  rendezvous  for  the  most  diverse 
systems,"  contributed  valuable  factors  to  the  century's  philosophical 
development,  both  of  a  negative  and  of  a  positive  character.  This 
thinker  was  peculiarly  fortunate  in  the  enrichment  of  the  conception 
of  experience  as  warranting  a  justifiable  confidence  in  the  ontological 
value  of  ethical,  sesthetical,  and  religious  sentiment  and  ideas;  but  he 
was  most  unfortunate  in  reviving  and  perpetuating  the  unjustifiable 
Kantian  distinction  between  cognition  and  faith  in  the  field  of  ex- 
perience. On  the  whole,  therefore,  the  Faith-philosophy  and  the 
Romantic  School  can  easily  be  said  to  have  contributed  more  than 
a  negative  and  modifying  influence  to  the  development  of  the  philo- 
sophy of  the  nineteenth  century.  Its  more  modern  revival  toward 
the  close  of  the  same  century,  and  its  continued  hold  upon  certain 
minds  of  the  present  day,  are  evidences  of  the  positive  but  partial 
truth  which  its  tenets,  however  vaguely  and  unsystematically,  con- 
tinue to  maintain  in  an  aesthetically  and  practically  attractive  way. 

The  admirers  of  Kant  strove  earnestly  and  with  varied  success 
to  remedy  the  defects  of  his  system.  Among  the  earlier,  less  cele- 
brated and  yet  important  members  of  this  group,  were  K.  G.  Rein- 
hold  (1758-1823),  and  Maimon  (died,  1800).  The  former,  hke 
Descartes,  in  that  he  was  educated  by  the  Jesuits,  began  the  attempt, 
after  rejecting  some  of  the  arbitrary  distinctions  of  Kant  and  his 
barren  and  self-contradictory  "Thing-in-itself,"  to  unify  the  critical 
philosophy  by  reducing  it  to  some  one  principle.  The  latter  really 
transcended  Kant  in  his  philosophical  skepticism,  and  anticipated  the 
Hamiltonian  form  of  the  so-called  principle  of  relativity.  Fries  (1773- 
1843),  and  Hermes  (1775-1831)  —  the  latter  of  whom  saw  in  empir- 
ical psychology  the  only  true  propaedeutic  to  philosophy  —  should  be 
mentioned  in  this  connection.  In  the  same  group  was  another,  both 
mathematician  and  philosopher,  who  strove  more  successfully  than 
others  of  this  group  to  accept  the  critical  standpoint  of  Kant  and  yet 
to  transcend  his  negative  conclusions  with  regard  to  a  theory  of 
knowledge.  I  refer  to  Bolzano  (Prague,  1781-1848),  who  stands  in  the 
same  line  of  succession  with  Fries  and  Hermes,  and  whose  works 
on  the  Science  of  Religion  (4  vols.  1834)  and  his  Science  of  Know- 


206  PHILOSOPHY 

ledge  (4  vols.  1837)  are  noteworthy  contributions  to  epistemological 
doctrine.  In  the  latter  we  have  developed  at  great  length  the  import- 
ant thought  that  the  illative  character  of  propositional  judgments 
implies  an  objective  relation;  and  that  in  all  truths  the  subject-idea 
must  be  objective.  In  the  work  on  religion  there  is  found  as  thor- 
oughly dispassionate  and  rational  a  defense  of  Catholic  doctrine  as 
exists  anywhere  in  philosophical  literature.  The  limited  influence  of 
these  works,  due  in  part  to  their  bulk  and  their  technical  character,  is 
on  the  whole,  I  think,  sincerely  to  be  regretted. 

It  was,  however,  chiefly  that  remarkable  series  of  philosophers 
which  may  be  grouped  under  the  rubric  of  a  "rational  Idealism," 
who  filled  so  full  and  made  so  rich  the  philosophical  life  of  Germany 
during  the  first  half  of  the  last  century;  whose  philosophical  thoughts 
and  systems  have  spread  over  the  entire  Western  World,  and  who  are 
most  potent  influences  in  shaping  the  development  of  philosophy 
down  to  the  present  hour.  Of  these  we  need  do  little  more  than  that 
we  can  do  —  mention  their  names.  At  their  head,  in  time,  stands 
Fichte,  who  —  although  Kant  is  reported  to  have  complained  of  this 
disciple  because  he  lied  about  him  so  much  —  really  divined  a  truth 
which  seems  to  be  hovering  in  the  clouds  above  the  master's  head, 
but  which,  if  the  critical  philosophy  truly  meant  to  teach  it,  needed 
helpful  deliverance  in  order  to  appear  in  perfectly  clear  light.  Fichte, 
although  he  divined  this  truth,  did  not,  however,  free  it  from  internal 
confusion  and  self-contradiction.  It  is  his  truth,  nevertheless,  that  in 
the  Self,  as  a  self-positing  and  self-determining  activity,  must  some- 
how be  found  the  Ground  of  all  experience  and  of  all  Reality. 

The  important  note  which  Schelling  sounded  was  the  demand  that 
philosophy  should  recognize  "Nature"  as  belonging  to  the  sphere 
of  Reality,  and  as  requiring  a  measure  of  reflective  thought  which 
should  in  some  sort  put  it  on  equal  terms  with  the  Ego,  for  the  con- 
struction of  our  conception  of  the  Being  of  the  World.  To  Schelling  it 
seemed  impossible  to  deduce,  as  Fichte  had  done,  all  the  rich  concrete 
development  of  the  world  of  things  from  the  subjective  needs  and  con- 
stitutional forms  of  functioning  which  belong  to  the  finite  Self.  And, 
indeed,  the  doctrine  which  limits  the  origin,  existence,  and  value  of 
all  that  is  known  about  this  sphere  of  experience  to  these  needs,  and 
which  finds  the  sufficient  account  of  all  experience  with  nature  in 
these  forms  of  functioning,  must  always  seem  inadequate  and  even 
grotesque  in  the  sight  of  the  natural  sciences.  Both  Nature  and  Spirit, 
thought  Schelling,  must  be  allowed  to  claim  actual  existence  and 
equally  real  value;  while  at  the  same  time  philosophy  must  reconcile 
the  seeming  opposition  of  their  claims  and  unite  them  in  an  har- 
monious and  self-explanatory  way.  In  some  common  substratum, 
in  which,  to  adopt  Hegel's  sarcastic  criticism,  as  in  the  darkness  of 
the  night  "all  cows  are  black,"  —  that  is  in  the  Absolute,  as  an 


PHILOSOPHY  IN   THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    207 

Identical  Basis  of  Differences,  —  the  reconciliation  was  to  be  accom- 
plished. 

But  the  constructive  idealistic  movement;  in  which  Fichte  and 
Schelling  bore  so  important  a  part,  could  not  be  satisfied  with  the 
positions  reached  by  either  of  these  two  philosophers.  Neither  the 
physical  and  psychological  sciences,  nor  the  speculative  interests  of 
religion,  ethics,  art,  and  social  life,  permitted  this  movement  to  stop 
at  this  point.  In  all  the  subsequent  developments  of  philosophy  dur- 
ing the  first  half  or  three  quarters  of  the  nineteenth  century,  undoubt- 
edly the  influence  of  Hegel  was  greatest  of  all  individual  thinkers.  His 
motif  and  plan  are  revealed  in  his  letter  of  November  2,  1800,  to 
Schelling,  namely,  to  transform  what  had  hitherto  been  an  ideal 
into  a  thoroughly  elaborate  system.  And  in  spite  of  his  obvious 
obscurities  of  thought  and  style,  there  is  real  ground  for  his  claim  to 
be  the  champion  of  the  common  consciousness.  It  is  undoubtedly  in 
Hegel's  Phdnomenologie  des  Geistes  (1807),  that  the  distinctive  fea- 
tures of  the  philosophy  of  the  first  half  of  the  last  century  most 
clearly  define  themselves.  The  forces  of  reflection  now  abandon  the 
abstract  analytic  method  and  positions  of  the  Kantian  Critique,  and 
concentrate  themselves  upon  the  study  of  man's  spiritual  life  as  an 
historical  evolution,  in  a  more  concrete,  face-to-face  manner.  Two 
important  and,  in  the  main,  valid  assumptions  underlie  and  guide 
this  reflective  study:  (1)  The  Ultimate  Reality,  or  principle  of  all 
realities,  is  Mind  or  Spirit,  which  is  to  be  recognized  and  known  in  its 
essence,  not  by  analysis  into  its  formal  elements  (the  categories), 
but  as  a  living  development;  (2)  those  formal  elements,  or  cate- 
gories to  which  Kant  gave  validity  merely  as  constitutional  forms 
of  the  functioning  of  the  human  understanding,  represent,  the  rather, 
the  essential  structure  of  Reality. 

In  spite  of  these  true  thoughts,  fault  was  justly  found  by  the  par- 
ticular sciences  with  both  the  speculative  method  of  Hegel,  which 
consists  in  the  smooth,  harmonious,  and  systematic  arrangement 
of  conceptions  in  logical  or  ideal  relations  to  one  another;  and  also 
with  the  result,  which  reduces  the  Being  of  the  World  to  terms  of 
thought  and  dialectical  processes  merely,  and  neglects  or  overlooks 
the  other  aspects  of  racial  experience.  Therefore,  the  idealistic 
movement  could  not  remain  satisfied  with  the  Hegelian  dialectic. 
Especially  did  both  the  religious  and  the  philosophical  party  revolt 
against  the  important  thought  underlying  Hegel's  philosophy  of 
religion;  namely,  that  "the  more  philosophy  approximates  to  a 
complete  development,  the  more  it  exhibits  the  same  need,  the  same 
interest,  and  the  same  content,  as  religion  itself."  This,  as  they 
interpreted  it,  meant  the  absorption  of  religion  in  philosophy. 

Next  after  Hegel,  among  the  great  names  of  this  period,  stand 
the  names  of  Herbart  and  Schopenhauer.    The  former  contributes 


208  PHILOSOPHY 

in  an  important  way  to  the  proper  conception  of  the  task  and  the 
method  of  philosophy,  and  influences  greatly  the  development  of 
psychology,  both  as  a  science  that  is  pedagogic  to  philosophy,  and  as 
laying  the  basis  for  pedagogical  principles  and  practice.  But  Herbart 
commits  again  the  ancient  fallacy,  under  the  spell  of  which  so  much  of 
the  Kantian  criticism  was  bound;  and  which  identifies  contradictions 
that  belong  to  the  imperfect  or  illusory  conceptions  of  individual 
thinkers  with  insoluble  antinomies  inherent  in  reason  itself.  In  spite 
of  the  little  worth  and  misleading  character  of  his  view  of  perception, 
and  the  quite  complete  inadequacy  of  the  method  by  which,  at  a 
single  leap,  he  reaches  the  one  all-explanatory  principle  of  his  philo- 
sophy, Schopenhauer  made  a  most  important  contribution  to  the 
reflective  thought  of  the  century.  It  is  true,  as  Kuno  Fischer  has 
said,  that  it  seems  to  have  occurred  to  Schopenhauer  only  twenty- 
five  years  after  he  had  propounded  his  theory,  that  will,  as  it  appears 
in  consciousness,  is  as  truly  phenomenal  as  is  intellect.  It  is  also  true 
that  his'  theory  of  knowledge  and  his  conception  of  Reality,  as  meas- 
ured by  their  powder  to  satisfy  and  explain  our  total  experience,  are 
inflicted  with  irreconcilable  contradictions.  Neither  can  we  accord 
firm  confidence  or  high  praise  to  the  "Way  of  Salvation"  which 
somehow  Will  can  attain  to  follow  by  Eesthetic  contemplation  and 
ascetic  self-denial.  Yet  the  philosophy  of  Schopenhauer  rightly 
insists  upon  our  Idealistic  construction  of  Reality  having  regard  to 
aspects  of  experience  which  his  predecessors  had  quite  too  much 
neglected;  and  even  its  spiteful  and  exaggerated  reminders  of  the 
facts  which  contradict  the  tendency  of  all  Idealism  to  construct  a 
smooth,  regular,  and  altogether  pleasing  conception  of  the  Being  of 
the  World,  have  been  of  great  benefit  to  the  development  of  the  latter 
half  of  the  nineteenth  century.  » 

In  estimating  the  thoughts  and  the  products  of  modern  Idealism 
we  ought  not  to  forget  the  larger  multitude  of  thoughtful  men,  both 
in  Germany  and  elsewhere,  who  have  contributed  toward  shaping 
the  course  of  reflection  in  the  attempt  to  answer  the  problems  which 
the  critical  philosophy  left  to  the  nineteenth  century.  It  is  a  singu- 
lar comment  upon  the  caprices  of  fame  that,  in  philosophy  as  in  sci- 
ence, politics,  and  art,  some  of  those  who  have  really  reasoned  most 
soundly  and  acutely,  if  not  also  effectively  upon  these  problems,  are 
little  known  even  by  name  in  the  history  of  the  philosophical  develop- 
ment of  the  century.  Among  the  earlier  members  of  this  group,  did 
space  permit,  we  should  wish  to  mention  Berger,  Solger,  Steffens, 
and  others,  who  strove  to  reconcile  the  positions  of  a  subjective  ideal- 
ism with  a  realistic  but  pantheistic  conception  of  the  Being  of  the 
World.  There  are  others,  who  like  Weisse,  I.  H.  Fichte,  C.  P. 
Fischer,  and  Braniss,  more  or  less  bitterly  or  moderately  and  reas- 
onably, opposed  the  method  and  the  conclusions  of  the  Hegelian  dia- 


PHILOSOPHY  IN   THE  NINETEENTH   CENTURY    209 

lectic.  Still  another  group  earned  for  themselves  the  supposedly 
opprobrious  but  decidedly  vague  title  of  "Dualists,"  by  rejecting 
what  they  conceived  to  be  the  pantheism  of  Hegel.  Still  others,  like 
Fries  and  Beneke  and  their  successors,  strove  to  parallel  philosophy 
with  the  particular  sciences  by  grounding  it  in  an  empirical  but 
scientific  psychology;  and  thus  they  instituted  a  line  of  closely  con- 
nected development,  to  which  reference  has  already  been  made. 

Hegel  himself  believed  that  he  had  permanently  effected  that 
reconcihation  of  the  orthodox  creed  with  the  cognition  of  Ultimate 
Reality  at  which  his  dialectic  aimed.  In  all  such  attempts  at  recon- 
ciliation three  great  questions  are  chiefly  concerned:  (1)  the  Being  of 
God;  (2)  the  nature  of  man;  (3)  the  actual  and  the  ideally  satisfac- 
tory relations  between  the  two.  But,  as  might  have  been  expected, 
a  period  of  wild,  irregular,  and  confused  contention  met  the  attempt 
to  establish  this  claim.  In  this  conflict  of  more  or  less  noisy  and 
popular  as  well  as  of  thoughtful  and  scholastic  philosophy,  Hegelians 
of  various  degrees  of  fidelity,  anti-Hegelians  of  various  degrees  of 
hostility,  and  ultra-Hegelians  of  various  degrees  of  eccentricity,  all 
took  a  valiant  and  conspicuous  part.  We  cannot  follow  its  history; 
but  we  can  learn  its  lesson.  Polemical  philosophy,  as  distinguished 
from  quiet,  reflective,  and  critical  but  constructive  philosophy  involves 
a  most  uneconomical  use  of  mental  force.  Yet  out  of  this  period  of 
conflict,  and  in  a  measure  as  its  result,  there  came  a  period  of  improved 
relations  between  science  and  philosophy  and  between  philosophy  and 
theology,  which  was  the  dawn,  toward  the  close  of  the  nineteenth 
century,  of  that  better  illumined  day  into  the  middle  of  which  we 
hope  that  we  are  proceeding. 

Before  leaving  this  idealistic  movement  in  Germany,  and  else- 
where as  influenced  largely  b}^  German  philosophy,  one  other  name 
deserves  mention.  This  name  is  that  of  Lotze,  who  combined  ele- 
ments from  many  previous  thinkers  with  those  derived  from  his  own 
studies  and  thoughts,  —  the  conceptions  of  mechanism  as  applied 
to  physical  existences  and  to  psychical  life,  with  the  search  for  some 
monistic  Principle  that  shall  satisfy  the  eesthetical  and  ethical,  as 
well  as  the  scientific  demands  of  the  human  mind.  This  variety  of 
interests  and  of  culture  led  to  the  result  of  his  making  important 
contributions  to  psychology,  logic,  metaphysics,  and  aesthetics.  If 
we  find  his  system  of  thinking  —  as  I  think  we  must  —  lacking  in 
certain  important  elements  of  consistency  and  obscured  in  places  by 
doubts  as  to  his  real  meaning,  this  does  not  prevent  us  from  assign- 
ing to  Lotze  a  position  which,  for  versatility  of  interests,  genial 
quality  of  reflection  and  criticism,  suggestiveness  of  thought  and 
charm  of  style,  is  second  to  no  other  in  the  history  of  nineteenth 
century  philosophical  development. 

In  France  and  in  England  the  first  quarter  of  the  last  century 


210  PHILOSOPHY 

was  far  from  being  productive  of  great  thinkers  or  great  thoughts  in 
the  sphere  of  philosophy.  De  Biran  (1766-1824),  in  several  important 
respects  the  forerunner  of  modern  psychology,  after  revolting  from 
his  earlier  complacent  acceptance  of  the  vagaries  of  Condillac  and 
Cabanis,  made  the  discovery  that  the  "immediate  consciousness  of 
self-activity  is  the  primitive  and  fundamental  principle  of  human 
cognition."  Meantime  it  was  only  a  little  group  of  Academicians  who 
were  being  introduced,  in  a  somewhat  superficial  way,  to  the  thoughts 
of  the  Scottish  and  the  German  idealistic  Schools  by  Royer-Collard, 
Jouffroy,  Cousin,  and  others.  A  more  independent  and  characteristic 
movement  was  that  inaugurated  by  Auguste  Comte  (1798-1857), 
who,  having  felt  the  marked  influence  of  Saint-Simon  when  he  was 
only  a  boy  of  twenty,  in  a  letter  to  his  friend  Valat,  in  the  year  1824, 
declares:  "I  shall  devote  my  whole  life  and  all  my  powers  to  the 
founding  of  positive  philosophy."  In  spite  of  the  impossibility  of 
harmonizing  with  this  point  of  view  the  vague  and  mystical  elements 
which  characterize  the  later  thought  of  Comte,  or  with  its  carrying 
into  effect  the  not  altogether  intelligent  recognition  of  the  synthetic 
activity  of  the  mind  (tout  se  reduit  toujours  a  lier)  and  certain  hints  as 
to  "first  principles;"  and  in  spite  of  the  small  positive  contribution 
to  philosophy  which  Comtism  could  claim  to  have  made;  it  has  in 
a  way  represented  the  value  of  two  ideas.  These  are  (1)  the  necessity 
for  philosophy  of  studying  the  actual  historical  forces  which  have 
been  at  work  and  which  are  displayed  in  the  facts  of  history;  and 
(2)  the  determination  not  to  go  by  mere  unsupported  speculation 
beyond  experience  in  order  to  discover  knowable  Reality.  There  is, 
however,  a  kind  of  subtle  irony  in  the  fact  that  the  word  "  Positivism  " 
should  have  come  to  stand  so  largely  for  negative  conclusions,  in  the 
very  spheres  of  philosophy,  morals,  and  religion  where  affirmative 
conclusions  are  so  much  desired  and  sought. 

That  philosophy  in  Great  Britain  was  in  a  nearly  complete  con- 
dition of  decadence  during  the  first  half  or  three  quarters  of  the 
nineteenth  century  was  the  combined  testimony  of  writers  from  such 
different  points  of  view  as  Carlyle,  Sir  William  Hamilton,  and  John 
Stuart  Mill.  And  yet  these  very  names  are  also  witnesses  to  the  fact 
that  this  decadence  was  not  quite  complete.  In  the  first  quarter  of 
the  century  Coleridge,  although  he  had  failed,  on  account  of  weakness 
both  of  mind  and  of  character,  in  his  attempt  to  reconcile  religion  to 
the  thought  of  his  own  age,  on  the  basis  of  the  Kantian  distinction  be- 
tween reason  and  the  intellect,  had  sowed  certain  seed-thoughts  which 
became  fertile  in  the  soil  of  minds  more  vigorous,  logical,  and  practi- 
cal than  his  own.  This  was,  perhaps,  especially  true  in  America,  where 
inquirers  after  truth  were  seeking  for  something  more  satisfactory 
than  the  French  skepticism  of  the  revolutionary  and  following  period. 
Carlyle 's  mocking  sarcasm  was  also  not  without  wholesome  effect. 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    211 

But  it  was  Sir  William  Hamilton  and  John  Stuart  Mill  whose 
thoughts  exercised  a  more  powerful  formative  influence  over  the 
minds  of  the  younger  men.  The  one  was  the  flower  of  the  Scottish 
Realism,  the  other  of  the  movement  started  by  Bentham  and  the 
elder  Mill. 

That  the  Scottish  Realism  should  end  by  such  a  combination 
with  the  skepticism  of  the  critical  philosophy  as  is  implied  in  Ham- 
ilton's law  of  the  relativity  of  all  knowledge,  is  one  of  the  most 
curious  and  interesting  turns  in  the  history  of  modern  philosophy. 
And  when  this  law  was  so  interpreted  by  Dean  Mansel  in  its  appli- 
cation to  the  fundamental  cognitions  of  religion  as  to  lay  the  founda- 
tions upon  which  the  most  imposing  structure  of  agnosticism  was 
built  by  Herbert  Spencer,  surely  the  entire  swing  around  the  circle, 
from  Kant  to  Kant  again,  has  been  made  complete.  The  attempt  of 
Hamilton  failed,  as  every  similar  attempt  must  always  fail.  Neither 
speculative  philosophy  nor  religious  faith  is  satisfied  with  an  ab- 
stract conception,  about  the  correlate  of  which  in  Reality  nothing 
is  known  or  ever  can  be  known.  But  every  important  attempt  of 
this  sort  serves  the  double  purpose  of  stimulating  other  efforts  to 
reconstruct  the  answer  to  the  problem  of  philosophy,  on  a  basis  of 
positive  experience  of  an  enlarged  type;  and  also  of  acting  as  a  real, 
if  only  temporary  practical  support  to  certain  value- judgments 
which  the  faiths  of  morality,  art,  and  religion  both  implicate  and, 
in  a  measure,  validate. 

The  influence  of  John  Stuart  Mill,  as  it  was  exerted  not  only  in 
his  conduct  of  life  while  a  servant  of  the  East  India  Company,  but 
also  in  his  writings  on  Logic,  Politics,  and  Philosophy,  was,  on  the 
whole,  a  valuable  contribution  to  his  generation.  In  the  additions 
which  he  made  to  the  Utilitarianism  of  Bentham  we  have  done,  I 
believe,  all  that  ever  can  be  done  in  defense  of  this  principle  of  ethics. 
And  his  posthumous  confessions  of  faith  in  the  ontological  value  of 
certain  great  conceptions  of  religion  are  the  more  valuable  because  of 
the  nature  of  the  man,  and  of  the  experience  which  is  their  source. 
Perhaps  the  most  permanent  contribution  which  Mill  made  to  the 
development  of  philosophy  proper,  outside  of  the  sphere  of  logic, 
ethics,  and  politics,  was  his  vigorous  polemical  criticism  of  Hamil- 
ton's claim  for  the  necessity  of  faith  in  an  "Unconditioned"  whose 
conception  is  "only  a  fasciculus  of  negations  of  the  Conditioned  in 
its  opposite  extremes,  and  bound  together  merely  by  the  aid  of 
language  and  their  common  character  of  incomprehensibility." 

The  history  of  the  development  of  philosophy  in  America  during 
the  nineteenth  century,  as  during  the  preceding  century,  has  been 
characterized  in  the  main  by  three  principal  tendencies.  These 
may  be  called  the  theological,  the  social,  and  the  eclectic.  From 
the  beginning  down  to  the  present  time  the  religious  influence  and 


212  ■       PHILOSOPHY 

the  interest  in  political  and  social  problems  have  been  dominant. 
And  yet  withal,  the  student  of  these  problems  in  the  atmosphere 
of  this  country  likes,  in  a  way,  to  do  his  own  thinking  and  to  make 
his  own  choices  of  the  thoughts  that  seem  to  him  true  and  best 
fitted  for  the  best  form  of  life.  In  spite  of  the  fact  that  the  different 
streams  of  European  thought  have  flowed  in  upon  us  somewhat 
freely,  there  has  been  comparatively  little  either  of  the  adherence 
to  schools  of  European  philosophy  or  of  the  attempt  to  develop  a 
national  school.  Doubtless  the  influence  of  English  and  Scottish 
thinking  upon  the  academical  circles  of  America  was  greatest  for 
more  than  one  hundred  and  fifty  years  after  the  gift  in  1714  by 
Governor  Yale  of  a  copy  of  Locke's  Essay  to  the  college  which  bore 
his  name,  —  and  especially  upon  the  reflections  and  published 
works  of  Jonathan  Edwards  touching  the  fundamental  problems 
of  epistemology,  ethics,  and  religion.  During  the  early  part  of  this 
century  these  views  awakened  antagonism  from  such  writers  as 
Dana,  Whedon,  Hazard,  Nathaniel  Taylor,  Jeremiah  Day,  Henry  P. 
Tappan,  and  other  opponents  of  the  Edwardean  theology,  and  also 
from  such  advocates  of  so-called  "free-thinking,"  as  had  derived 
their  motifs  and  their  views  from  English  deistical  writers  like 
Shaftesbury,  or  from  the  skepticism  of  Hume. 

A  more  definite  philosophical  movement,  however,  which  had 
established  itself  somewhat  firmly  in  scholastic  centres  by  the  year 
1825,  and  which  maintained  itself  for  more  than  half  a  century, 
went  back  to  the  arrival  in  this  country  of  John  Witherspoon,  in 
1768,  to  be  the  president  of  Princeton,  bringing  with  him  a  library 
of  three  hundred  books.  It  was  the  appeal  of  the  Scottish  School  to 
the  "plain  man's  consciousness"  and  to  so-called  "common  sense," 
which  was  relied  upon  to  controvert  all  forms  of  philosophy  which 
seemed  to  threaten  the  foundations  of  religion  and  of  the  ethics 
of  politics  and  sociology.  But  even  during  this  period,  which  was 
characterized  by  relatively  little  independent  thinking  in  scholastic 
circles,  a  more  pronounced  productivity  was  shown  by  such  writers 
as  Francis  Wayland,  and  others;  but,  perhaps,  especially  by  Laurens 
P.  Hickok,  whose  works  on  psychology  and  cosmology  deserve 
especial  recognition:  while  in  psychology,  as  related  to  philosophical 
problems,  the  principal  names  of  this  period  are  undoubtedly  the 
presidents  of  Yale  and  Princeton,  —  Noah  Porter  and  James  Mc- 
Cosh,  —  both  of  whom  (but  especially  the  former)  had  their  views 
modified  by  the  more  scientific  psychology  of  Europe  and  the  pro- 
founder  thinking  of  Germany. 

It  was  Germany's  influence,  however,  both  directly  and  indirectly 
through  Coleridge  and  a  few  other  English  writers,  that  caused  a 
ferment  of  impressions  and  ideas  which,  in  their  effort  to  work  them- 
selves clear,  resulted  in  what  is  known  as  New  England  "Tran- 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE   NINETEENTH  CENTURY    213 

scendentalism/^  In  America  this  movement  can  scarcely  be  called 
definitely  philosophical;  much  less  can  it  be  said  to  have  resulted 
in  a  system,  or  even  in  a  school,  of  philosophy.  It  must  also  be  said 
to  have  been  "inspired  but  not  borrowed"  from  abroad.  Its  prin- 
cipal, if  not  sole,  literary  survival  is  to  be  found  in  the  works  of  Emer- 
son. As  expounded  by  him,  it  is  not  precisely  Pantheism  —  certainly 
not  a  consistent  and  critical  development  of  the  pantheistic  theory 
of  the  Being  of  the  World;  it  is,  rather,  a  vague,  poetical,  and  pan- 
theistical Idealism  of  a  decidedly  mystical  type. 

The  introduction  of  German  philosophy  proper,  in  its  nature  form, 
and  essential  being,  to  the  few  interested  seriously  in  critical  and 
reflective  thinking  upon  the  ultimate  problems  of  nature  and  of 
human  life,  began  with  the  founding  of  the  Journal  of  Speculative 
Philosophy,  in  1867,  under  the  direction  of  William  T.  Harris,  then 
Superintendent  of  Schools  in  this  city. 

With  the  work  of  Darwin,  and  his  predecessors  and  successors, 
there  began  a  mighty  movement  of  thought  which,  although  it  is 
primarily  scientific  and  more  definitely  available  in  biological  science, 
has  already  exercised,  and  is  doubtless  destined  to  exercise  in  the 
future,  an  enormous  influence  upon  philosophy.  Indeed,  we  are 
already  in  the  midst  of  the  preliminary  confusions  and  contentions, 
but  most  fruitful  considerations  and  discoveries  belonging  to  a 
so-called  philosophy  of  evolution. 

This  development  has,  in  the  sphere  of  systematic  philosophy, 
reached  its  highest  expression  in  the  voluminous  works  produced 
through  the  latter  half  of  the  nineteenth  century  by  Mr.  Herbert 
Spencer,  whose  recent  death  seems  to  mark  the  close  of  the  period 
we  have  under  consideration.  The  metaphysical  assumptions  and 
ontological  value  of  the  system  of  Spencer,  as  he  wished  it  to  be 
understood  and  interpreted,  have  perhaps,  though  not  unnaturally, 
been  quite  too  much  submerged  in  the  more  obvious  expressions  of 
its  agnostic  positivism.  In  its  psychology,  however,  the  assumption 
of  "some  underlying  substance  in  contrast  to  all  changing  forms," 
distinguishes  it  from  a  pure  positivism  in  a  very  radical  way.  But 
more  especially  in  philosophy,  the  metaphysical  postulate  of  a 
mysterious  Unity  of  Force  that  somehow  manages  to  reveal  itself, 
and  the  law  of  its  operations,  to  the  developed  cognition  of  the 
nineteenth  century  philosopher,  however  much  it  seems  to  involve 
the  system  in  internal  contradictions,  certainly  forbids  that  we 
should  identify  it  with  the  positivism  of  Auguste  Comte.  In  our 
judgment,  however,  it  is  in  his  ethical  good  sense  and  integrity  of 
judgment,  —  a  good  sense  and  integrity  which  commits  to  ethics 
rather  than  to  sociology  the  task  of  determining  the  highest  type 
of  human  life,  —  and  in  basing  the  conditions  for  the  prevalence  and 
the  development  of  the  highest  type  of  life  upon  ethical  principles 


214  PHILOSOPHY 

and  upon  the  adherence  to  ethical  ideas,  that  Herbert  Spencer  will 
be  found  most  clearly  entitled  to  a  lasting  honor. 

III.  The  third  number  of  our  difScult  tasks  is  to  summarize  the 
principal  results,  to  inventory  the  net  profits,  as  it  were,  of  the  devel- 
opment of  philosophy  during  the  nineteenth  century.  This  task  is 
made  the  more  difficult  by  the  heterogeneous  nature  and  as  yet 
unclassified  condition  of  the  development.  With  the  quickening 
and  diversifying  of  all  kinds  and  means  of  intercourse,  there  has 
come  the  breaking-down  of  national  schools  and  idiosyncrasies  of 
method  and  of  thought.  In  philosophy,  Germany,  France,  Great 
Britain,  and  indeed,  Italy,  have  come  to  intermingle  their  streams 
of  infiuence;  and  from  all  these  countries  these  streams  have  been 
flowing  in  upon  America.  In  psychology,  especially,  as  well  as  in  all 
the  other  sciences,  but  also  to  some  degree  in  philosophy,  returning 
streams  of  influence  from  America  have,  during  the  last  decade  or 
two,  been  felt  in  Europe  itself. 

It  must  also  be  admitted  that  the  attempts  at  a  reconstruction  of 
systematic  philosophy  which  have  followed  the  rapid  disintegration 
of  the  Hegelian  system,  and  the  enormous  accumulations  of  new 
material  due  to  the  extension  of  historical  studies  and  of  the  par- 
ticular sciences, — including  especially  the  so-called  "new  psycho- 
logy, "  —  have  not  as  yet  been  fruitful  of  large  results.  In  philo- 
sophy, as  in  art,  politics,  and  even  scientific  theory,  the  spirit  and 
the  opportunity  of  the  time  are  more  favorable  to  the  gathering  of 
material  and  to  the  projecting  of  a  bewildering  variety  of  new  opin- 
ions, or  old  opinions  put  forth  under  new  names,  than  to  that  candid, 
patient,  and  prolonged  reflection  and  balancing  of  judgment  which 
a  worthy  system-building  inexorably  requires.  The  age  of  breaking  up 
the  old,  without  assimilating  the  new,  has  not  yet  passed  away.  And 
whatever  is  new,  startling,  large,  even  monstrous,  has  in  many 
quarters  the  seeming  preference,  in  philosophy's  building  as  in  other 
architecture.  To  the  confusion  which  reigns  even  in  scholastic 
circles,  contributions  have  been  arriving  from  the  outside,  from 
philosophers  like  Nietzsche,  and  from  men  great  in  literature  like 
Tolstoi.  Nor  has  the  matter  been  helped  by  the  more  recent  extreme 
developments  of  positivism  and  skepticism,  which  often  enough, 
without  any  consciousness  of  their  origin  and  without  the  respect 
for  morality  and  religion  which  Kant  always  evinced,  really  go  back 
to  the  critical  philosophy. 

In  spite  of  all  this,  however,  the  last  two  decades  or  more  have 
shown  certain  hopeful  tendencies  and  notable  achievements,  look- 
ing toward  the  reconstruction  of  systematic  philosophy.  In  this 
attempt  to  bring  order  out  of  confusion,  to  enable  calm,  prolonged, 
and  reflective  thinking  to  build  into  its  structure  the  riches  of  the 
new  material  which  the  evolution  of  the  race  has  secured,  a  place 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    215 

of  honor  ought  to  be  given  to  France,  where  so  much  has  been  done 
of  late  to  blend  with  clearness  of  style  and  independence  of  thought 
that  calm  reflective  and  critical  judgment  which  looks  all  sides  of 
human  experience  sympathetically  but  bravely  in  the  face.  In 
psychology  Ribot,  and  in  philosophy,  Fouillee,  Renouvier,  Secretan, 
and  others,  deserve  grateful  recognition.  No  friend  of  philosophy 
can,  I  think,  fail  to  recognize  the  probable  benefits  to  be  derived 
from  that  movement  with  which  such  names  as  Mach  and  Ostwald 
in  Germany  are  connected,  and  which  is  sounding  the  call  to  the 
men  of  science  to  clear  up  the  really  distressing  obscurity  and  con- 
fusion which  has  so  long  clung  to  their  fundamental  conceptions; 
and  to  examine  anew  the  significance  of  their  assumptions,  with 
a  view  to  the  construction  of  a  new  and  improved  doctrine  of  the 
Being  of  the  World.  And  if  to  these  names  we  add  those  of  the 
numerous  distinguished  investigators  of  psychology  as  pedagogic 
to  philosophy,  and,  in  philosophy,  of  Deussen,  Eucken,  von  Hart- 
mann,  Riehl,  Wundt,  and  others,  we  may  well  affirm  that  new  light 
will  continue  to  break  forth  from  that  country  which  so  powerfully 
aroused  the  whole  Western.  World  at  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  and 
beginning  of  the  nineteenth  centuries.  In  Great  Britain  the  name 
and  works  of  Thomas  Hill  Green  have  influenced  the  attempts  at 
a  reconstruction  of  systematic  philosophy  in  a  manner  to  satisfy  at 
one  and  the  same  time  both  the  facts  and  laws  of  science  and  the 
sesthetical,  ethical,  and  religious  ideals  of  the  age,  in  a  very  consider- 
able degree.  And  in  this  attempt,  both  as  it  expresses  itself  in  theo- 
retical psychology  and  in  the  various  branches  of  philosophical 
discipline,  writers  like  Bradley,  Eraser,  Flint,  Hodgson,  Seth,  Stout, 
Ward,  and  others,  have  taken  a  conspicuous  part.  Nor  are  there 
wanting  in  Holland,  Italy,  and  even  in  Sweden  and  Russia,  thinkers 
equally  worthy  of  recognition,  and  recognized,  in  however  limited 
and  unworthy  fashion,  in  their  own  land.  The  names  of  those  in 
America  who  have  labored  most  faithfully,  and  succeeded  best,  in 
this  enormous  task  of  reconstructing  philosophy  in  a  systematic 
way,  and  upon  a  basis  of  history  and  of  modern  science,  I  do  not 
need  to  mention;  they  are  known,  or  they  surely  ought  to  be  known, 
to  us  all. 

In  attempting  to  summarize  the  gains  of  philosophy  during  the 
last  hundred  years,  we  should  remind  ourselves  that  progress  in 
philosophy  does  not  consist  in  the  final  settlement,  and  so  in  the 
"solving"  of  any  of  its  great  problems.  Indeed,  the  relations  of 
philosophy  to  its  grounds  in  experience,  and  the  nature  of  its  method 
and  of  its  ideal,  are  such  that  its  progress  can  never  be  expected 
to  put  an  end  to  itself.  But  the  content  of  the  total  experience  of 
humanity  has  been  greatly  enriched  during  the  last  century;  and 
the  critical  and  reflective  thought  of  trained  minds  has  been  led 


216  PHILOSOPHY 

toward  a  more  profound  and  comprehensive  theory  of  ReaUty, 
and  toward  a  doctrine  of  values  that  shall  be  more  available  for  the 
improvement  of  man's  political,  social,  and  religious  life. 

In  view  of  this  truth  respecting  the  limitations  of  systematic 
philosophy,  I  think  we  may  hold  that  certain  negative  results, 
which  are  customarily  adduced  as  unfavorable  to  the  claims  of 
philosophical  progress,  are  really  signs  of  improvement  during  the 
latter  half  of  the  nineteenth  century.  One  is  an  increased  spirit 
of  reserve  and  caution,  and  an  increased  modesty  of  claims.  This 
result  is  perhaps  significant  of  riper  wisdom  and  more  trustworthy 
maturity.  Kant  believed  himself  to  have  established  for  philosophy 
a  system  of  apodeictic  conclusions,  which  were  as  completely  forever 
to  have  displaced  the  old  dogmatism  as  Copernicus  had  displaced 
the  Ptolemaic  astronomy.  But  the  steady  pressure  of  historical  and 
scientific  studies  has  made  it  increasingly  difficult  for  any  sane 
thinker  to  claim  for  any  system  of  thinking  such  demonstrable  val- 
idity. May  we  not  hope  that  the  students  of  the  particular  sciences, 
to  whom  philosophy  owes  so  much  of  its  enforced  sanity  and  sane 
modesty,  will  themselves  soon  share  freely  of  the  philosophic  spirit 
with  regard  to  their  own  metaphysics  and  ethical  and  religious 
standpoints,  touching  the  Ultimate  Reality?  Even  when  the  recoil 
from  the  overweening  self-satisfaction  and  crass  complacency  of  the 
earher  part  of  the  last  century  takes  the  form  of  melancholy,  or  of 
acute  sadness,  or  even  of  a  mild  despair  of  philosophy,  I  am  not  sure 
that  the  last  state  of  that  man  is  not  better  than  the  first. 

In  connection  with  this  improvement  in  spirit,  we  may  also  note  an 
improvement  in  the  method  of  philosophy.  The  purely  speculative 
method,  with  its  intensely  interesting  but  indefensible  disregard  of 
concrete  facts,  and  of  the  conclusions  of  the  particular  sciences,  is  no 
longer  in  favor  even  among  the  most  ardent  devotees  and  advocates 
of  the  superiority  of  philosophy  to  those  sciences.  At  the  same  time, 
philosophy  may  quite  properly  continue  to  maintain  its  position  of 
independent  critic,  as  well  as  of  docile  pupil,  toward  the  particular 
sciences. 

In  the  same  connection  must  be  mentioned  the  hopeful  fact  that 
the  last  two  or  three  decades  have  shown  a  decided  improvement  in 
the  relations  of  philosophy  toward  the  positive  sciences.  There  are 
plain  signs  of  late  that  the  attitude  of  antagonism,  or  of  neglect, 
which  prevailed  so  largely  during  the  second  and  third  quarters  of  the 
nineteenth  century,  is  to  be  replaced  by  one  of  friendship  and  mutual 
helpfulness.  And,  indeed,  science  and  philosophy  cannot  long  or 
greatly  flourish  without  reciprocal  aid,  if  by  science  we  mean  a  true 
Wissenschaft  and  if  we  also  mean  to  base  philosophy  upon  our  total 
experience.  For  science  and  philosophy  are  really  engaged  upon  the 
same  task,  —  to  understand  and  to  appreciate  the  totality  of  man's 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    217 

experience.  They,  therefore,  have  essential  and  permanent  relations 
of  dependence  for  material,  for  inspiration  and  correction,  and  for 
other  forms  of  helpfulness.  While,  then,  their  respective  spheres  have 
been  more  clearly  delimited  during  the  last  century,  their  inter- 
dependence has  been  more  forcefully  exhibited.  Both  of  them  have 
been  developing  a  systematic  exposition  of  the  universe.  Both 
of  them  desire  to  enlarge  and  deepen  the  conception  of  the  Being  of 
the  World,  as  made  known  to  the  totality  of  human  experience,  in 
its  Unity  of  nature  and  significance.  We  cannot  believe  that  the  end 
of  the  nineteenth  century  would  sustain  the  charge  which  Fontenelle 
made  in  the  closing  years  of  the  seventeenth  century:  '' L'Acade?nie 
des  Sciences  ne  prend  la  nature  que  par  petites  parcelles."  Science  itself 
now  bids  us  regard  the  Universe  as  a  dynamical  Unity,  teleologically 
conceived,  because  in  a  process  of  evolution  under  the  control  of 
immanent  ideas.  Philosophy  assumes  the  same  point  of  view,  rather 
at  the  beginning  than  at  the  end  of  defining  its  purpose;  and  so  feels 
a  certain  glad  leap  at  its  heart-strings,  and  an  impulse  to  hold  out 
the  hand  to  science,  when  it  hears  such  an  utterance  as  that  of  Poin- 
care:    Ce  n'est  pas  le  mechanisme  le  vrai,  le  seul  hut  ;  c'est  Vunite. 

Shall  we  not  say,  then,  that  this  double-faced  but  wholly  true 
lesson  has  been  learned:  namely,  that  the  so-called  philosophy  of 
nature  has  no  sound  foundation  and  no  safeguard  against  vagaries 
of  every  sort,  unless  it  follows  the  lead  of  the  positive  sciences  of 
nature;  but  that  the  sciences  themselves  can  never  afford  a  full 
satisfaction  to  the  legitimate  aspirations  of  human  reason  unless  they, 
too,  contribute  to  the  philosophy  of  nature  —  writ  large  and  con- 
ceived of  as  a  real-ideal  Unity. 

That  nature,  as  known  and  knowable  by  man,  is  a  great  artist, 
and  that  man's  sesthetical  consciousness  may  be  trusted  as  having 
a  certain  ontological  value,  is  the  postulate  properly  derived  from  the 
considerations  advanced  in  the  latest,  and  in  some  respects  the  most 
satisfactory,  of  the  three  Critiques  of  Kant.  The  ideal  way  of  looking 
at  natural  phenomena  which  so  delighted  the  mind  of  Goethe  has  now 
been  placed  on  broad  and  sound  foundations  by  the  fruitful  indus- 
tries of  many  workmen,  —  such  as  Karl  Ernst  von  Baer  and  Charles 
Darwin,  —  whose  morphological  and  evolutionary  conceptions  of  the 
universe  have  transformed  the  current  conceptions  of  cosmic  pro- 
cesses. But  the  world  of  physical  and  natural  phenomena  has  thereby 
been  rendered  not  less,  but  more,  of  a  Cosmos,  an  orderly  totality. 

In  addition  to  these  more  general  but  somewhat  vague  evaluations 
of  the  progress  of  philosophy  during  the  nineteenth  century,  we  are 
certainly  called  upon  to  face  the  question  whether,  after  all,  any 
advance  has  been  made  toward  the  more  satisfactory  solution  of  the 
definite  problems  which  the  Kantian  criticism  left  unsolved.  To  this 
question  I  believe  an  affirmative  answer  may  be  given  in  accordance 


218  PHILOSOPHY 

with  the  facts  of  history.  It  will  be  remembered  that  the  first  of  these 
problems  was  the  epistemological.  Certainly  no  little  improvement 
has  been  made  in  the  psychology  of  cognition.  We  can  no  longer 
repeat  the  mistakes  of  Kant,  either  tvith  respect  to  the  uncritical 
assumptions  he  makes  regarding  the  origin  of  knowledge  in  the 
so-called  "faculties"  of  the  human  mind  or  regarding  the  analysis 
of  those  faculties  and  their  interdependent  relations.  It  is  not  the 
Scottish  philosophy  alone  which  has  led  to  the  conclusion  that,  in  the 
word  of  the  late  Professor  Adamson,  "  What  are  called  acts  or  states 
of  consciousness  are  not  rightly  conceived  of  as  having  for  their 
objects  their  own  modes  of  existence  as  ways  in  which  a  subject  is 
modified."  And  in  the  larger  manner  both  science  and  philosophy,  in 
their  negations  and  their  affirmations,  and  even  in  their  points  of 
view,  have  better  grounds  for  the  faith  of  human  reason  in  its  power 
progressively  to  master  the  knowledge  of  Reality  than  was  the  case 
a  hundred  years  ago.  Nor  has  the  skepticism  of  the  same  era,  whether 
by  shallow  scoffing  at  repeated  failures,  or  by  pious  sighs  over  the 
limitations  of  human  reason,  or  by  critical  analysis  of  the  cognitive 
faculties  "according  to  well-established  principles,"  succeeded  in 
limiting  our  speculative  pretensions  to  the  sphere  of  possible  expe- 
rience,—  in  the  Kantian  meaning  both  of  "principles"  and  of 
"experience."  But  what  both  science  and  philosophy  are  com- 
pelled to  agree  upon  as  a  common  underlying  principle  is  this:  The 
proof  of  the  most  fundamental  presuppositions,  as  well  as  of  the 
latest  more  scientifically  established  conclusions,  of  both  science  and 
philosophy,  is  the  assistance  they  afford  in  the  satisfactory  explana- 
tion of  the  totality  of  racial  experience. 

In  the  evolution  of  the  ontological  problem,  as  compared  with  the 
form  in  which  it  was  left  by  the  critical  philosophy,  the  past  century 
has  also  made  some  notable  advances.  To  deny  this  would  be  to  dis- 
credit the  development  of  human  knowledge  so  far  as  to  say  that  we 
know  no  more  about  what  nature  is,  and  man  is,  than  was  known 
a  hundred  years  ago.  To  say  this,  however,  would  not  be  to  speak 
truth  of  fact.  And  here  we  may  not  unnaturally  grow  somewhat 
impatient  with  that  metaphysical  fallacy  which  places  an  impassable 
gulf  between  Reality  and  Experience.  No  reality  is,  of  course,, 
cognizable  or  believable  by  man  which  does  not  somehow  show  its 
presence  in  his  total  experience.  But  no  growth  of  experience  is  pos- 
sible without  involving  increase  of  knowledge  representing  Reality. 
For  Reality  is  no  absent  and  dead,  or  statical,  Ding-an-Sich.  Cogni- 
tion itself  is  a  commerce  of  realities.  And  are  there  not  plain  signs 
that  the  more  thoughtful  men  of  science  are  becoming  less  averse  to 
the  recognition  of  the  truth  of  ontological  philosophy;  namely,  that 
the  deeper  meaning  of  their  own  studies  is  grasped  only  when  they 
recognize  that  they  are  ever  face  to  face  with  what  they  call  Energy 


PHILOSOPHY  IN   THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    219 

and  we  call  Will,  and  with  what  they  call  laws  and  we  call  Mind  as 
significant  of  the  progressive  realization  of  immanent  ideas.  This 
Ultimate  Reality  is  so  profound  that  neither  science  nor  philosophy 
will  ever  sound  all  its  depths,  and  so  comprehensive  as  more  than  to 
justify  all  the  categories  of  both. 

Probably,  on  the  whole,  there  has  been  less  progress  made  toward  a 
satisfactory  solution  of  the  problems  offered  by  the  value-judgments 
of  ethics  and  religion,  in  the  form  in  which  these  problems  were  left 
by  the  critical  philosophy.  The  century  has  illustrated  the  truth  of 
Falckenberg's  statement:  "In  periods  which  have  given  birth  to  a 
skeptical  philosophy,  one  never  looks  in  vain  for  the  complementary 
phenomenon  of  mysticism."  Twice  during  the  century  the  so-called 
"faith-philosophy,"  or  philosophy  of  feeling,  has  been  borne  to  the 
front,  to  raise  a  bulwark  against  the  advancing  hosts  of  agnostics  — 
occasioned  in  the  first  period  by  the  negations  of  the  Kantian  criti- 
cism, and  in  the  second  by  the  positive  conclusions  of  the  physical 
and  biological  sciences.  This  form  of  protesting  against  the  neglect 
or  disparagement  of  important  factors  which  belong  to  man's  ses- 
thetical,  ethical,  and  religious  experience,  is  reasonable  and  must  be 
heard.  But  the  extravagances  with  which  these  neglected  factors 
have  been  posited  and  appraised,  to  the  neglect  of  the  more  defini- 
tively scientific  and  strictly  logical,  is  to  be  deplored.  The  great  work 
before  the  philosophy  of  the  present  age  is  the  reconciliation  of  the 
historical  and  scientific  conceptions  of  the  Universe  with  the  legiti- 
mate sentiments  and  ideals  of  art,  morality,  and  religion.  But  surely 
neither  rationalism  nor  "faith-philosophy"  is  justified  in  pouring  out 
the  living  child  with  the  muddy  water  of  the  bath. 

IV.  The  attempt  to  survey  the  present  situation  of  philosophy, 
and  to  predict  its  immediate  future,  is  embarrassed  by  the  fact  that 
we  are  all  immersed  in  it,  are  a  part  of  its  spirit  and  present  form. 
But  if  nearness  has  its  embarrassments,  it  has  also  its  benefits.  Those 
who  are  amidst  the  tides  of  life  may  know  better,  in  a  way,  how  these 
tides  are  tending  and  what  is  their  present  strength,  than  do  those 
who  survey  them  from  distant,  cool,  and  exalted  heights.  "Fur 
jeden  einzelnen  hildet  der  Vater  und  der  Sohn  eine  greifbare  Kette  von 
Lehensereignungen  und  Erfahrungen."  The  very  intensely  vital  and 
formative  but  unformed  condition  of  systematic  philosophy  —  its 
protoplasmic  character  —  contains  promises  of  a  new  life.  If  we 
may  believe  the  view  of  Hegel  that  the  systematizing  of  the  thought 
of  any  age  marks  the  time  when  the  peculiar  living  thought  of  that 
age  is  passing  into  a  period  of  decay,  we  may  certainly  claim  for  our 
present  age  the  prospect  of  a  prolonged  vitality. 

The  nineteenth  century  has  left  us  with  a  vast  widening  of  the 
horizon,  —  outward  into  space,  backward  in  time,  inward  toward  the 
secrets  of  life,  and  downward  into  the  depths  of  Reality.    With  this 


220  PHILOSOPHY 

there  has  been  an  increase  in  the  profundity  of  the  conviction  of  the 
spiritual  unity  of  the  race.  In  the  consideration  of  all  of  its  problems 
in  the  immediate  future  and  in  the  coming  century  —  so  far  as  we  can 
see  forward  into  this  century  —  philosophy  will  have  to  reckon  with 
certain  marked  characteristics  of  the  human  spirit  which  form  at  the 
same  time  inspiring  stimuli  and  limiting  conditions  of  its  endeavors 
and  achievements.  Chief  among  these  are  the  greater  and  more 
firmly  established  principles  of  the  positive  sciences,  and  the  pre- 
valence of  the  historical  spirit  and  method  in  the  investigation  of  all 
manner  of  problems.  These  influences  have  given  shape  to  the  con- 
ception which,  although  it  is  as  yet  by  no  means  in  its  final  or  even 
in  thoroughly  self-consistent  form,  is  destined  powerfully  to  affect 
our  philosophical  as  well  as  our  scientific  theories.  This  conception  is 
that  of  Development.  But  philosophy,  considered  as  the  product  of 
critical  and  reflective  thinking  over  the  more  ultimate  problems  of 
nature  and  of  human  life,  is  itself  a  development.  And  it  is  now,  more 
than  ever  before,  a  development  interdependently  connected  with  all 
the  other  great  developments. 

Philosophy,  in  order  to  adapt  itself  to  the  spirit  of  the  age,  must 
welcome  and  cultivate  the  freest  critical  inquiry  into  its  own  methods 
and  results,  and  must  cheerfully  submit  itself  to  the  demand  for 
evidences  which  has  its  roots  in  the  common  and  essential  experience 
of  the  race.  Moreover,  the  growth  of  the  spirit  of  democracy,  which, 
on  the  one  hand,  is  distinctly  unfavorable  to  any  system  of  philosophy 
whose  tenets  and  formulas  seem  to  have  only  an  academic  validity 
or  a  merely  esoteric  value,  and  which,  on  the  other  hand,  requires 
for  its  satisfaction  a  more  tenable,  helpful,  and  universally  appli- 
cable theory  of  life  and  reality,  cannot  fail,  in  my  judgment,  to  influ- 
ence favorably  the  development  of  philosophy.  In  the  union  of  the 
speculative  and  the  practical;  in  the  harmonizing  of  the  interests  of 
the  positive  sciences,  with  their  judgments  of  fact  and  law,  and  the 
interests  of  art,  morality,  and  religion,  with  their  value-judgments 
and  ideals;  in  the  synthesis  of  the  truths  of  Realism  and  Idealism,  as 
they  have  existed  hitherto  and  now  exist  in  separateness  or  antago- 
nism; in  a  union  that  is  not  accomplished  by  a  shallow  eclecticism,  but 
by  a  sincere  attempt  to  base  philosophy  upon  the  totality  of  human 
experience;  —  in  such  a  union  as  this  must  we  look  for  the  real  pro- 
gress of  philosophy  in  the  coming  century. 

Just  now  there  seem  to  be  two  somewhat  heterogeneous  and  not 
altogether  well-defined  tendencies  toward  the  reconstruction  of  sys- 
tematic philosophy,  both  of  which  are  powerful  and  represent  real 
truths  conquered  by  ages  of  intellectual  industry  and  conflict.  These 
two,  however,  need  to  be  internally  harmonized,  in  order  to  obtain  a 
satisfactory  statement  of  the  development  of  the  last  century.  They 
may  be  called  the  evolutionary  and  the  idealistic.   The  one  tendency 


PHILOSOPHY  IN   THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    221 

lays  emphasis  on  mechanism,  the  other  on  spirit.  Yet  it  is  most 
interesting  to  notice  how  many  of  the  early  workmen  in  the  investi- 
gation of  the  principle  of  the  conservation  and  correlation  of  energy 
took  their  point  of  departure  from  distinctly  teleological  and  spiritual 
conceptions.  "  I  was  led/'  said  Colding,  —  to  take  an  extreme  case,  — 
at  the  Natural  Science  Congress  at  Innsbruck,  1869,  "  to  the  idea  of 
the  constancy  of  national  forces  by  the  religious  conception  of  life." 
And  even  Moleschott,  in  his  Autobiography,  posthumously  published, 
declares :  "  I  myself  was  well  aware  that  the  whole  conception  might 
be  converted;  for  since  all  matter  is  a  bearer  of  force,  endowed  with 
force  or  penetrated  with  spirit,  it  would  be  just  as  correct  to  call  it 
a  spiritualistic  conception."  On  the  other  hand,  the  modern,  better 
instructed  Idealism  is  much  inclined,  both  from  the  psychological  and 
from  the  more  purely  philosophical  points  of  view,  to  regard  with 
duly  profound  respect  all  the  facts  and  laws  of  that  mechanism  of 
Reality,  which  certainly  is  not  merely  the  dependent  construction 
of  the  human  mind  functioning  according  to  a  constitution  that 
excludes  it  from  Reality,  but  is  rather  the  ever  increasingly  more 
trustworthy  revealer  of  Reality.  This  tendency  to  a  union  of  the 
claims  of  both  Realism  and  Idealism  is  profoundly  influencing  the 
solution  of  each  one  of  these  problems  which  the  Kantian  criticism 
left  to  the  philosophy  of  the  nineteenth  century.  In  respect  of  the 
epistemological  problem,  philosophy  —  as  I  have  already  said  — 
is  not  likely  again  to  repeat  the  mistakes  either  of  Kant  or  of  the 
dogmatism  which  his  criticism  so  effectually  overthrew.  It  was  a 
wise  remark  of  the  physician  Johann  Benjamin  Erhard,  in  a  letter 
dated  May  19,  1794,  a  propos  of  Fichte:  "The  philosophy  which 
proceeds  from  a  single  fundamental  principle,  and  pretends  to  deduce 
everything  from  it,  is  and  always  will  remain  a  piece  of  artificial 
sophistry:  only  that  philosophy  which  ascends  to  the  highest  prin- 
ciple and  exhibits  everything  else  in  perfect  harmony  with  it,  is  the 
true  one."  This  at  least  ought — one  would  say  —  to  have  been 
made  clear  by  the  century  of  discussion  over  the  epistemological 
problem,  since  Kant.  You  cannot  deduce  the  Idea  from  the  Reality, 
or  the  Reality  from  the  Idea.  The  problem  of  knowledge  is  not,  as 
Fichte  held  in  the  form  of  a  fundamental  assumption,  an  alternative 
of  this  sort.  The  Idea  and  Reality  are,  the  rather  already  there, 
and  to  be  recognized  as  in  a  living  unity,  in  every  cognitive  experi- 
ence. Psychology  is  constantly  adding  something  toward  the  pro- 
blem of  cognition  as  a  problem  in  synthesis;  and  is  then  in  a  way 
contributing  to  the  better  scientific  understanding  of  the  philo- 
sophical postulate  which  is  the  confidence  of  human  reason  in  its 
ability,  by  the  harmonious  use  of  all  its  powers,  progressively  to 
reach  a  better  and  fuller  knowledge  of  Reality. 

The  ontological  problem  will  necessarily  always  remain  the  un- 


222  PHILOSOPHY 

solved,  in  the  sense  of  the  very  incompletely  solved  problem  of 
philosophy.  But  as  long  as  human  experience  develops,  and  as  long 
as  philosophy  bestows  upon  experience  the  earnest  and  candid 
efforts  of  reflecting  minds,  the  solution  of  the  ontological  problem 
will  be  approached,  but  never  fully  reached.  That  Being  of  the 
World  which  Kant,  in  the  negative  and  critical  part  of  his  work, 
left  as  an  X,  unknown  and  unknowable,  the  last  century  has  filled 
with  a  new  and  far  richer  content  than  it  ever  had  before.  Especially 
has  this  century  changed  the  conception  of  the  Unity  of  the  Uni- 
verse in  such  manner  that  it  can  never  return  again  to  its  ancient 
form.  On  the  one  hand,  this  Unity  cannot  be  made  comprehensible 
in  terms  of  any  one  scientific  or  philosophical  principle  or  law. 
Science  and  philosophy  are  both  moving  farther  and  farther  away 
from  the  hope  of  comprehending  the  variety  and  infinite  manifold- 
ness  of  the  Absolute  in  terms  of  any  one  side  or  aspect  of  man's 
complex  experience.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  the  confidence  in  this 
essential  Unity  is  not  diminished,  but  is  the  rather  confirmed.  As 
humanity  itself  develops,  as  the  Selfhood  of  man  grows  in  the 
experience  of  the  world  which  is  its  own  environment,  and  of  the 
world  within  which  it  is  its  own  true  Self,  humanity  may  reasonably 
hope  to  win  an  increased,  and  increasingly  valid,  cognition  of  the 
Being  of  the  World  as  the  Absolute  Self. 

Closely  connected,  and  in  a  way  essentially  identical  with  the 
ontological  problem,  is  that  of  the  origin,  validity,  and  rational 
value  of  the  ideas  of  humanity.  May  it  not  be  said  that  the  nine- 
teenth century  transfers  to  the  twentieth  an  increased  interest  in 
and  a  heightened  appreciation  of  the  so-called  practical  problems 
ef  philosophy.  Science  and  philosophy  certainly  ought  to  combine 
—  and  are  they  not  ready  to  combine?  —  in  the  effort  to  secure 
a  more  nearly  satisfactory  understanding  and  solution  of  the  pro- 
blems afforded  by  the  sesthetical,  ethical,  and  religious  sentiments 
and  ideals  of  the  race.  To  philosophy  this  combination  means  that 
it  shall  be  more  fruitful  than  ever  before  in  promoting  the  uplift  and 
betterment  of  mankind.  The  fulfillment  of  the  practical  mission  of 
philosophy  involves  the  application  of  its  conceptions  and  prin- 
ciples to  education,  politics,  morals,  as  a  matter  of  law  and  of  cus- 
tom, and  to  religion  as  matter  both  of  rational  faith  and  of  the  con- 
duct of  life. 

How,  then,  can  this  brief  and  imperfect  sketch  of  the  outline  of  the 
development  of  philosophy  in  the  nineteenth  century  better  come  to 
a  close  than  by  words  of  encouragement  and  of  exhortation  as  well. 
There  are,  in  my  judgment,  the  plainest  signs  that  the  somewhat 
too  destructive  and  even  nihilistic  tendencies  of  the  second  and 
third  quarters  of  the  nineteenth  century  have  reached  their  limit; 
that  the  strife  of  science  and  philosophy,  and  of  both  with  religion, 


PHILOSOPHY  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY     223 

is  lessening,  and  is  being  rapidly  displaced  by  the  spirit  of  mutual 
fairness  and  reciprocal  helpfulness;  and  that  reasonable  hopes  of 
a  new  and  a  splendid  era  of  reconstruction  in  philosophy  may  be 
entertained.  For  I  cannot  agree  with  the  dictum  of  a  recent  writer 
on  the  subject,  that  "  the  sciences  are  coming  less  and  less  to  admit 
of  a  synthesis,  and  not  at  all  of  a  synthetic  philosopher." 

On  the  contrary,  I  hold  that,  with  an  increased  confidence  in  the 
capacity  of  human  reason  to  discover  and  validate  the  most  secret 
and  profound,  as  well  as  the  most  comprehensive,  of  truths,  philo- 
sophy may  well  put  aside  some  of  its  shyness  and  hesitancy,  and  may 
resume  more  of  that  audacity  of  imagination,  sustained  by  ontological 
convictions,  which  characterized  its  work  during  the  first  half  of  the 
nineteenth  century.  And  if  the  latter  half  of  the  twentieth  century 
does  for  the  constructions  of  the  first  half  of  the  same  century,  what 
the  latter  half  of  the  nineteenth  century  did  for  the  first  half  of  that 
century,  this  new  criticism  will  only  be  to  illustrate  the  way  in  which 
the  human  spirit  makes  every  form  of  its  progress. 

Therefore,  a  summons  of  all  helpers,  in  critical  but  fraternal  spirit, 
to  this  work  of  reconstruction,  for  which  two  generations  of  enormous 
advance  in  the  positive  sciences  has  gathered  new  material,  and  for 
the  better  accomplishment  of  which  both  the  successes  and  the 
failures  of  the  philosophy  of  the  nineteenth  century  have  prepared 
the  men  of  the  twentieth  century,  is  the  winsome  and  imperative 
voice  of  the  hour. 


SECTION  A  — METAPHYSICS 


SECTION  A  — METAPHYSICS 


{Hall  6,  September  21,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Professor  A.  C.  Armstrong,  Wesleyan  University. 
Speakers:     Professor  A.  E.  Taylor,  McGill  University,  Montreal. 

Professor  Alexander  T.  Ormond,  Princeton  University. 
Secretary:  Professor  A.  O.  Lovejoy,  Washington  University. 

The  Chairman  of  the  Section,  Professor  A.  C.  Armstrong,  of  Wes- 
leyan University,  in  opening  the  meeting  referred  to  the  contin- 
ued vitahty  of  metaphysics  as  shown  by  its  repeated  revivals  after 
the  many  destructive  attacks  upon  it  in  the  later  modern  times: 
he  congratulated  the  Section  on  the  fact  that  the  principal  speakers 
were  scholars  who  had  made  notable  contributions  to  metaphysical 
theory. 


THE    RELATIONS    BETWEEN    METAPHYSICS    AND    THE 
OTHER   SCIENCES 

BY    PEOFESSOR    ALFRED    EDWARD    TAYLOR 

[Alfred  Edward  Taylor,  Frothingham  Professor  of  Philosophy,  McGill  Uni- 
versity, Montreal,  Canada,  b.  Oundle,  England,  December  22,  1869.  M.A. 
Oxford.  Fellow,  Merton  College,  Oxford,  1891-98,  1902- ;  Lecturer  in 
Greek  and  Philosophy,  Owens  College,  Manchester,  1896-1903;  Assistant 
Examiner  to  University  of  Wales,  1899-1903;  Green  Moral  Philosophy  Prize- 
man, Oxford,  1899;  Frothingham  Professor  of  Philosophy,  McGill  Uni- 
versity, 1903- ;  Member  Philosophical  Society,  Owens  College,  American 
Philosophical  Association.  Author  of  The  Problem  of  Conduct;  Elements  of 
Metaphysics.] 

When  we  seek  to  determine  the  place  of  metaphysics  in  the  gen- 
eral scheme  of  human  knowledge,  we  are  at  once  confronted  by  an 
initial  difficulty  of  some  magnitude.  There  seems,  in  fact,  to  be  no 
one  universally  accepted  definition  of  our  study,  and  even  no  very 
general  consensus  among  its  votaries  as  to  the  problems  with  which 
the  metaphysician  ought  to  concern  himself.  This  difficulty,  serious 
as  it  is,  does  not,  however,  justify  the  suspicion  that  our  science  is, 
like  alchemy  or  astrology,  an  illusion,  and  its  high-sounding  title 
a  mere  "idol  of  the  market-place,"  one  of  those  nomina  rerum  quae 
non  sunt  against  which  the  Chancellor  Bacon  has  so  eloquently 
warned  mankind.    If  it  is  hard  to  determine  precisely  the  scope  of 


228  METAPHYSICS 

metaphysics,  it  is  no  less  difficult  to  do  the  same  thing  for  the  un- 
doubtedly legitimate  sciences  of  logic  and  mathematics.  And  in  all 
three  cases  the  absence  of  definition  merely  shows  that  we  are  deal- 
ing with  branches  of  knowledge  which  are,  so  to  say,  still  in  the 
making.  It  is  not  until  the  first  principles  of  science  are  already 
firmly  laid  beyond  the  possibility  of  cavil  that  we  must  look  for 
general  agreement  as  to  its  boundary  lines,  though  excellent  work 
may  be  done,  long  before  this  point  has  been  reached,  in  the  estab- 
lishment of  individual  principles  and  deduction  of  consequences 
from  them.  To  revert  to  the  parallel  cases  I  have  just  cited,  many 
mathematical  principles  of  the  highest  importance  are  formulated  in 
the  Elements  of  Euclid,  and  many  logical  principles  in  the  Organon 
of  Aristotle;  yet  it  is  only  in  our  own  time  that  it  has  become  possible 
to  offer  a  general  definition  either  of  logic  or  of  mathematics,  and 
even  now  it  would  probably  be  true  to  say  that  the  majority  of 
logicians  and  mathematicians  trouble  themselves  very  little  about 
the  precise  definition  of  their  respective  studies. 

The  state  of  our  science  then  compels  me  to  begin  this  address 
with  a  more  or  less  arbitrary,  because  provisional,  definition  of  the 
term  metaphysics,  for  which  I  claim  no  more  than  that  it  may  serve 
to  indicate  with  approximate  accuracy  the  class  of  problems  which 
I  shall  have  in  view  in  my  subsequent  use  of  the  word.  By  meta- 
physics, then,  I  propose  to  understand  the  inquiry  which  used 
formerly  to  be  known  as  ontology,  that  is,  the  investigation  into  the 
general  character  which  belongs  to  real  Being  as  such,  the  science,  in 
Aristotelian  phraseology,  of  ovra  ■§  ovra.  Or,  if  the  term  "  real "  be 
objected  against  as  ambiguous,  I  would  suggest  as  an  alternative 
account  the  statement  that  metaphysics  is  the  inquiry  into  the  general 
character  by  which  the  content  of  true  assertions  is  distinguished 
from  that  of  jalse  assertions.  The  two  definitions  here  offered  will, 
I  think,  be  found  equivalent  when  it  is  borne  in  mind  that  what  the 
second  of  them  speaks  of  is  exclusively  the  content  which  is  asserted 
as  true  in  a  true  proposition,  not  the  process  of  true  assertion,  which, 
like  all  other  processes  in  the  highest  cerebral  centres,  falls  under 
the  consideration  of  the  vastly  different  sciences  of  psychology  and 
cerebral  physiology.  Of  the  two  equivalent  forms  of  statement,  the 
former  has  perhaps  the  advantage  of  making  it  most  clear  that  it 
is  ultimately  upon  the  objective  distinction  between  the  reality  and 
the  unreality  of  that  which  is  asserted  for  truth,  and  not  upon  any 
psychological  peculiarity  in  the  process  of  assertion  itself  that  the 
distinction  between  true  and  untrue  rests,  while  the  second  may  be 
useful  in  guarding  against  misconceptions  that  might  be  suggested 
by  too  narrow  an  interpretation  of  the  term  ''  reality,"  such  as,  e.  g., 
the  identification  of  the  "  real"  with  what  is  revealed  by  sensuous 
perception. 


METAPHYSICS  AND   THE  OTHER  SCIENCES       229 

From  the  acceptance  of  such  a  definition  two  important  conse- 
quences would  follow.  (1)  The  first  is  that  metaphysics  is  at  once 
sharply  discriminated  from  any  study  of  the  psychical  process  of 
knowledge,  if  indeed,  there  can  be  any  such  study  distinct  from  the 
psychology  of  conception  and  belief,  which  is  clearly  not  itself  the 
science  we  have  in  view.  For  the  psychological  laws  of  the  formation 
of  concepts  and  beliefs  are  exemplified  equally  in  the  discovery  and 
propagation  of  truth  and  of  error.  And  thus  it  is  in  vain  to  look  to 
them  for  any  explanation  of  the  difference  between  the  two.  Nor 
does  the  otherwise  promising  extension  of  Darwinian  conceptions 
of  the  "struggle  for  existence"  and  the  ''survival  of  the  fittest" 
to  the  field  of  opinions  and  convictions  appear  to  affect  this  con- 
clusion. Such  considerations  may  indeed  assist  us  to  understand 
how  true  convictions  in  virtue  of  their  "  usefulness"  gradually  come 
to  be  established  and  extended,  but  they  require  to  presume  the 
truth  of  these  convictions  as  an  antecedent  condition  of  their  "  use- 
fulness" and  consequent  establishment.  I  should  infer,  then,  that 
it  is  a  mistake  in  principle  to  seek  to  replace  ontology  by  a  "  theory 
of  knowledge,"  and  should  even  be  inclined  to  question  the  very 
possibility  of  such  a  theory  as  distinct  from  metaphysics  on  the  one 
hand  and  empirical  psychology  on  the  other.  (2)  The  second  con- 
sequence is  of  even  greater  importance.  The  inquiry  into  the  gen- 
eral character  by  which  the  contents  of  true  assertions  are  discrim- 
inated from  the  contents  of  false  assertions  must  be  carefully  dis- 
tinguished from  any  investigation  into  the  truth  or  falsehood  of 
special  assertions.  To  ask  how  in  the  end  truth  differs  from  falsehood 
is  to  raise  an  entirely  different  problem  from  that  created  by  asking 
whether  a  given  statement  is  to  be  regarded  as  true  or  false.  The  dis- 
tinction becomes  particularly  important  when  we  have  to  deal  with 
what  Locke  would  call  assertions  of  "real  existence,"  i.  e.,  assertions 
as  to  the  occurrence  of  particular  events  in  the  temporal  order.  All 
such  assertions  depend,  in  part  at  least,  upon  the  admission  of  what 
we  may  style  "empirical"  evidence,  the  immediate  unanalyzed 
witness  of  simple  apprehension  to  the  occurrence  of  an  alleged 
matter  of  fact.  Thus  it  would  follow  from  our  proposed  conception 
of  metaphysics  that  metaphysics  is  in  principle  incapable  either  of 
establishing  or  refuting  any  assertion  as  to  the  details  of  our  immedi- 
ate experience  of  empirical  fact,  though  it  may  have  important  bear- 
ings upon  any  theory  of  the  general  nature  of  true  Being  which  we 
may  seek  to  found  upon  our  alleged  experiences.  In  a  word,  if  our 
conception  be  the  corre'ct  one,  the  functions  of  a  science  of  meta- 
physics in  respect  of  our  knowledge  of  the  temporal  sequence  of 
events  psychical  and  physical  must  be  purely  critical,  never  con- 
structive, —  a  point  to  which  I  shall  presently  have  to  recur. 

One  more  general  reflection,  and  we  may  pass  to  the  consideration 


230  METAPHYSICS 

of  the  relation  of  metaphysics  to  the  various  already  organzied 
branches  of  human  knowledge  more  in  detail.  The  admission  that 
there  is,  or  may  be,  such  a  study  as  we  have  described,  seems  of  itself 
to  involve  the  recognition  that  definite  knowledge  about  the  character 
of  what  really  "  is, "  is  attainable,  and  thus  to  commit  us  to  a  position 
of  sharp  opposition  both  to  consistent  and  thorough-going  agnos- 
ticism and  also  to  the  latent  agnosticism  of  Kantian  and  neo-Kant- 
ian  "critical  philosophy."  In  recognizing  ontology  as  a  legitimate 
investigation,  we  revert  in  principle  to  the  "dogmatist"  position 
common,  e.  g.,  to  Plato,  to  Spinoza  and  to  Leibniz,  that  there  is  genu- 
ine truth  which  can  be  known,  and  that  this  genuine  truth  is  not 
confined  to  statements  about  the  process  of  knowing  itself.  In 
fact,  the  "critical"  view  that  the  only  certain  truth  is  truth  about 
the  process  of  knowing  seems  to  be  inherently  self-contradictory. 
For  the  knowledge  that  such  a  proposition  as,  e.  g.,  "  I  know  only 
the  laws  of  my  own  apprehending  activity, "  is  true,  would  itself  be 
knowledge  not  about  the  process  of  knowing  but  about  the  content 
known.  Thus  metaphysics,  conceived  as  the  science  of  the  general 
character  which  distinguishes  truth  from  falsehood,  presupposes 
throughout  all  knowledge  the  presence  of  what  we  may  call  a  "  tran- 
scendent object,"  that  is,  a  content  which  is  never  identical  with 
the  process  by  which  it  is  apprehended,  though  it  may  no  doubt  be 
maintained  that  the  two,  the  process  and  its  content,  if  distinct,  are 
yet  not  ultimately  separable.  That  they  are  in  point  of  fact  not 
ultimately  separable  would  seem  to  be  the  doctrine  which,  under 
various  forms  of  statement,  is  common  to  and  characteristic  of  all  the 
"idealistic"  systems  of  metaphysics.  So  much  then  in  defense  of  a 
metaphysical  point  of  view  which  seems  to  be  closely  akin  to  that 
of  Mr.  Bradley  and  of  Professor  Royce,  to  mention  only  two  names 
of  contemporary  philosophers,  and  which  might,  I  think,  for  the 
purpose  of  putting  it  in  sharp  opposition  to  the  "  neo-Kantian " 
view,  not  unfairly  be  called,  if  it  is  held  to  need  a  name,  "neo- 
Leibnizian." 

In  passing  on  to  discuss  in  brief  the  nature  of  the  boundary  lines 
which  divide  metaphysics  from  other  branches  of  study,  it  seems 
necessary  to  start  with  a  clear  distinction  between  the  "pure"  or 
"formal"  and  the  "applied"  or  "empirical"  sciences,  the  more  so 
as  in  the  loose  current  employment  of  language  the  name  "  science  " 
is  frequently  given  exclusively  to  the  latter.  In  every-day  life,  when 
we  are  told  that  a  certain  person  is  a  "man  of  science,"  or  as  the 
detestable  jargon  of  our  time  likes  to  say,  a  "scientist, "  we  expect  to 
find  that  he  is,  e.g.,  a  geologist,  a  chemist,  a  biologist,  or  an  electrician. 
We  should  be  a  little  surprised  to  find  on  inquiry  that  our  "  man  of 
science"  was  a  pure  mathematician,  and  probably  more  than  a  little 
to  learn  that  he  was  a  formal  logician.    The  distinction  between  the 


METAPHYSICS   AND   THE  OTHER  SCIENCES       231 

pure  and  the  empirical  sciences  may  be  roughly  indicated  by  saying 
that  the  latter  class  comprises  all  those  sciences  which  yield  infor- 
mation about  the  particular  details  of  the  temporal  order  of  events 
phj^sical  and  psychical,  whereas  the  pure  sciences  deal  solely  with  the 
general  characteristics  either  of  all  truths,  or  of  all  truths  of  some 
well-defined  class.  More  exactly  we  may  say  that  the  marks  by 
which  an  empirical  is  distinguished  from  a  pure  science  are  two. 
(1)  The  empirical  sciences  one  and  all  imply  the  presence  among 
their  premises  of  empirical  propositions,  that  is,  propositions  which 
assert  the  actual  occurrence  of  some  temporal  fact,  and  depend  upon 
the  witness  of  immediate  apprehension,  either  in  the  form  of  sense- 
perception  or  in  that  of  what  is  commonly  called  self -consciousness. 
In  the  vague  language  made  current  by  Kant,  they  involve  an  appeal 
to  some  form  of  unanalyzed  "intuition."  The  pure  sciences,  on  the 
other  hand,  contain  no  empirical  propositions  either  among  their  pre- 
mises or  their  conclusions.  The  principles  which  form  their  premises 
are  self-evidently  true  propositions,  containing  no  reference  to  the 
actual  occurrence  of  any  event  in  the  temporal  order,  and  thus  in- 
volving no  appeal  to  any  form  of  "intuition."  And  the  conclusions 
established  in  a  pure  science  are  all  rigidly  logical  deductions  from 
such  self-evident  premises.  That  the  universality  of  this  distinction 
is  still  often  overlooked  even  by  professed  writers  on  scientific  method 
seems  explicable  by  two  simple  considerations.  On  the  one  hand,  it 
is  easy  to  overlook  the  important  distinction  between  a  principle 
which  is  self-evident,  that  is,  which  cannot  be  denied  without  explicit 
falsehood,  and  a  proposition  affirmed  on  the  warrant  of  the  senses, 
because,  though  its  denial  cannot  be  seen  to  be  obviously  false, 
the  senses  appear  on  each  fresh  appeal  to  substantiate  the  asser- 
tion. Thus  the  Euclidean  postulate  about  parallels  was  long  falsely 
supposed  to  possess  exactly  the  same  kind  of  self-evidence  as 
the  dictum  de  omni  and  the  principle  of  identity  which  are  part 
of  the  foundations  of  all  logic.  And  further  Kanf,  writing  under 
.  the  influence  of  this  very  confusion,  has  given  wide  popularity  to 
the  view  that  the  best  known  of  the  pure  sciences,  that  of  mathe- 
matics, depends  upon  the  admission  of  empirical  premises  in  the 
form  of  an  appeal  to  intuition  of  the  kind  just  described.  Fortunately 
the  recent  developments  of  arithmetic  at  the  hands  of  such  men 
as  Weierstrass,  Cantor,  and  Dedekind  seem  to  have  definitely  refuted 
the  Kantian  view  as  far  as  general  arithmetic,  the  pure  science  of 
number,  is  concerned,  by  proving  that  one  and  all  of  its  propositions 
are  analytic  in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word,  that  is,  that  they  are 
capable  of  rigid  deduction  from  self-evident  premises,  so  that,  in 
what  regards  arithmetic,  we  may  say  with  Schroder  that  the  famous 
Kantian  question  "how  are  sjmthetic  judgments  a  priori  possible?" 
is  now  known  to  be  meaningless.    As  regards  geometry,  the  case  ap- 


232  METAPHYSICS 

pears  to  a  non-mathematician  like  myself  more  doubtful.  Those 
who  hold  with  Schroder  that  geometry  essentially  involves,  as  Kant 
thought  it  did,  an  appeal  to  principles  not  self-evident  and  depend- 
ent upon  an  appeal  to  sensuous  "intuition,"  are  logically  bound 
to  conclude  with  him  that  geometry  is  an  "  empirical,"  or  as  W.  K. 
Clifford  called  it,  a  "physical"  science,  different  in  no  way  from 
mechanics  except  in  the  relative  paucity  of  the  empirical  premises 
presupposed,  and  to  class  it  with  the  applied  sciences.  On  the  other 
hand,  if  Mr.  Bertrand  Russell  should  be  successful  in  his  promised 
demonstration  that  all  the  principles  of  geometry  are  deducible  from 
a  few  premises  which  include  nothing  of  the  nature  of  an  appeal  to 
sensuous  diagrams,  geometry  too  would  take  its  place  among  the 
pure  sciences,  but  only  on  condition  of  our  recognizing  that  its 
truths,  like  those  of  arithmetic,  are  one  and  all,  as  Leibniz  held, 
strictly  analytical.  Thus  we  obtain  as  a  first  distinction  between  the 
pure  and  the  empirical  sciences  the  principle  that  the  propositions 
of  the  former  class  are  all  analytical,  those  of  the  latter  all  synthetic. 
It  is  not  the  least  of  the  services  which  France  is  now  rendering  to 
the  study  of  philosophy  that  we  are  at  last  being  placed  by  the 
labors  of  M.  Couturat  in  a  position  to  appreciate  at  their  full  worth 
the  views  of  the  first  and  greatest  of  German  philosophers  on  this 
distinction,  and  to  understand  how  marvelously  they  have  been 
confirmed  by  the  subsequent  history  of  mathematics  and  of  logic. 

(2)  A  consequence  of  this  distinction  is  that  only  the  pure  or 
formal  sciences  can  be  matter  of  rigid  logical  demonstration.  Since 
the  empirical  or  applied  sciences  one  and  all  contain  empirical  pre- 
mises, i.  e.,  premises  which  we  admit  as  true  only  because  they  have 
always  appeared  to  be  confirmed  by  the  appeal  to  "  intuition," 
and  not  because  the  denial  of  them  can  be  shown  to  lead  to  false- 
hood, the  conclusions  to  which  they  conduct  us  must  one  and  all 
depend,  in  part  at  least,  upon  induction  from  actual  observation  of 
particular  temporal  sequences.  This  is  as  much  as  to  say  that  all 
propositions  in  the  applied  sciences  involve  somewhere  in  the  course 
of  the  reasoning  by  which  they  are  established  the  appeal  to  the 
calculus  of  Probabilities,  which  is  our  one  method  of  eliciting  general 
results  from  the  statistics  supplied  by  observation  or  experiment. 
That  this  is  the  case  with  the  more  concrete  among  such  applied 
sciences  has  long  been  universally  acknowledged.  That  it  is  no  less 
true  of  sciences  of  such  wide  range  as  mechanics  may  be  said,  I 
think,  to  have  been  definitely  established  in  our  own  day  by  the 
work  of  such  eminent  physicists  as  Kirchhoff  and  Mach.  In  fact, 
the  recent  developments  of  the  science  of  pure  number,  to  which 
reference  has  been  made  in  a  preceding  paragraph,  combined  with 
the  creation  of  the  "descriptive  "  theory  of  mechanics,  may  fairly 
be  said  to  have  finally  vindicated  the  distinction  drawn  by  Leibniz 


METAPHYSICS  AND  THE  OTHER  SCIENCES       233 

long  ago  between  the  truths  of  reason  and  the  truths  of  empirical 
fact,  a  distinction  which  the  Kantian  trend  of  philosophical  specu- 
lation tended  during  the  greater  part  of  the  nineteenth  century  to 
obscure,  while  it  was  absolutely  ignored  by  the  empiricist  opponents 
of  metaphysics  both  in  England  and  in  Germany.  The  philosoph- 
ical consequences  of  a  revival  of  the  distinction  are,  I  conceive,  of 
far-reaching  importance.  On  the  one  side,  recognition  of  the  em- 
pirical and  contingent  character  of  all  general  propositions  estab- 
lished by  induction  appears  absolutely  fatal  to  the  current  mechan- 
istic conception  of  the  universe  As  a  realm  of  purposeless  sequences 
unequivocally  determined  by  unalterable  "laws  of  nature,"  a  result 
which  has  in  recent  years  been  admirably  illustrated  for  the  Eng- 
lish-speaking world  by  Professor  Ward's  weU-known  Gifford  lectures 
on  "Naturalism  and  Agnosticism."  Laws  of  physical  nature,  on  the 
empiristic  view  of  applied  science,  can  mean  no  more  than  observed 
regularities,  obtained  by  the  application  of  the  doctrine  of  chances, 
—  regularities  which  we  are  indeed  justified  in  accepting  with  con- 
fidence as  the  basis  for  calculation  of  the  future  course  of  temporal 
sequence,  but  which  we  have  no  logical  warrant  for  treating  as  ulti- 
mate truths  about  the  final  constitution  of  things.  Thus,  for  exam- 
ple, take  the  common  assumption  that  our  physical  environment 
is  composed  of  a  multitude  of  particles  each  in  every  respect  the 
exact  counterpart  of  every  other.  Reflection  upon  the  nature  of 
the  evidence  by  which  this  conclusion,  if  supported  at  all,  has  to 
be  supported,  should  convince  us  that  at  most  all  that  the  state- 
ment ought  to  mean  is  that  individual  differences  between  the  ele- 
mentary constituents  of  the  physical  world  need  not  be  allowed 
for  in  devising  practical  formulae  for  the  intelligent  anticipation  of 
events.  When  the  proposition  is  put  forward  as  an  absolute  truth 
and  treated  as  a  reason  for  denying  the  ultimate  spirituality  of  the 
world,  we  are  well  within  our  rights  in  declining  the  consequence 
on  the  logical  ground  that  conclusions  from  an  empirical  premise 
must  in  their  o-rti  nature  be  themselves  empirical  and  contingent. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  extreme  empiricism  which  treats  all  know- 
ledge whatsoever  as  merely  relative  to  the  total  psychical  state 
of  the  knower,  and  therefore  in  the  end  problematic,  must,  I  appre- 
hend, go  down  before  any  serious  investigation  into  the  nature  of 
the  analytic  truths  of  arithmetic,  a  consequence  which  seems  to  be 
of  some  relevance  in  connection  with  the  philosophic  view  popularly 
known  as  Pragmatism.  Thus  I  should  look  to  the  coming  regeneration 
of  metaphysics,  of  which  there  are  so  many  signs  at  the  moment,  on 
the  one  hand,  for  emphatic  insistence  on  the  right,  e.  g.,  of  physics 
and  biology  and  psychology  to  be  treated  as  purely  empirical 
sciences,  and  as  such  freed  from  the  last  vestiges  of  any  domination 
by  metaphysical  presuppositions  and  foregone  conclusions,  and  on 


234  METAPHYSICS 

the  other,  for  an  equally  salutary  purgation  of  formal  studies  like 
logic  and  arithmetic  from  the  taint  of  corruption  by  the  irrelevant 
intrusion  of  considerations  of  empirical  psychology. 

We  cannot  too  persistently  bear  in  mind  that  there  is,  correspond- 
ing to  the  logical  distinction  between  the  analytic  and  the  synthetic 
proposition,  a  deep  and  broad  general  difference  between  the  wants 
of  our  nature  ministered  to  by  the  formal  and  the  applied  sciences 
respectively.  The  formal  sciences,  incapable  of  adding  anything  to 
our  detailed  knowledge  of  the  course  of  events,  as  we  have  seen, 
enlighten  us  solely  as  to  the  general  laws  of  interconnection  by  which 
all  conceivable  systems  of  true  assertions  are  permeated  and  bound 
together.  In  a  different  connection  it  would  be  interesting  to  de- 
velop further  the  reflection  that  the  necessity  of  appealing  to  such 
formal  principles  in  all  reasoning  about  empirical  matters  of  fact 
contains  the  explanation  of  the  famous  Platonic  assertion  that  the 
''Idea  of  Good"  or  supreme  principle  of  organization  and  order  in 
the  universe,  is  itself  not  an  existent,  but  something  en  i-n-eKava  t^9 
ovcTLa?,  "transcending  even  existence,"  and  the  very  similar  declara- 
tion of  Hegel  that  the  question  whether  "God"  —  in  the  sense  of 
such  a  supreme  principle  —  exists  is  frivolous,  inasmuch  as  existence 
(Dasein)  is  a  category  entirely  inadequate  to  express  the  Divine 
nature.  For  my  present  purpose  it  is  enough  to  remark  that  the 
need  to  which  the  formal  sciences  minister  is  the  demand  for  that 
purely  speculative  satisfaction  which  arises  from  insight  into  the 
order  of  interconnection  between  the  various  truths  w^hich  compose 
the  totality  of  true  knowledge.  Hence  it  seems  a  mistake  to  say,  as 
some  theorists  have  done,  that  were  we  born  with  a  complete  know- 
ledge of  the  course  of  temporal  sequences  throughout  the  universe, 
and  a  faultless  memory,  we  should  have  no  need  of  logic  or  meta- 
physics, or  in  fact  of  inference.  For  even  a  mind  already  in  possession 
of  all  true  propositions  concerning  the  course  of  events,  would  still 
lack  one  of  the  requisites  for  complete  intellectual  satisfaction 
unless  it  were  also  aware,  not  only  of  the  individual  truths,  but  of 
the  order  of  their  interdependence.  What  Aristotle  said  long  ago 
with  reference  to  a  particular  instance  may  be  equally  said  univers- 
ally of  all  our  empirical  knowledge;  ''even  if  we  stood  on  the 
moon  and  saw  the  earth  intercepting  the  light  of  the  sun,  we  should 
still  have  to  ask  for  the  reason  why."  The  purposes  ministered  to 
by  the  empirical  sciences,  on  the  other  hand,  always  include  some  re- 
ference to  the  actual  manipulation  in  advance  by  human  agency  of 
the  stream  of  events.  We  study  mechanics,  for  instance,  not  merely 
that  we  may  perceive  the  interdependence  of  truths,  but  that  we 
may  learn  how  to  maintain  a  system  of  bodies  in  equilibrium,  or  how 
to  move  masses  in  a  given  direction  with  a  given  momentum.  Hence 
it  is  true  of  applied  science,  though  untrue  of  science  as  a  whole,  that 


METAPHYSICS  AND   THE  OTHER  SCIENCES       235 

it  would  become  useless  if  the  whole  past  and  future  course  of  events 
were  from  the  first  familiar  to  us.  And,  incidentally  it  may  be  ob- 
served, it  is  for  the  same  reason  untrue  of  inference,  though  true  of 
inductive  inference,  that  it  is  essentially  a  passage  from  the  known 
to  the  unknown. 

In  dealing  with  the  relation  of  metaphysics  to  the  formal  sciences 
generally,  the  great  difficulty  w^hich  confronts  us  is  that  of  determin- 
ing exactly  the  boundaries  which  separate  one  from  another.  Among 
such  pure  sciences  we  have  by  universal  admission  to  include  at 
least  two,  pure  formal  logic  and  pure  mathematics,  as  distinguished 
from  the  special  applications  of  logic  and  mathematics  to  an  empiri- 
cal material.  Whether  we  ought  also  to  recognize  ethics  and  aesthet- 
ics, in  the  sense  of  the  general  determination  of  the  nature  of  the 
good  and  the  beautiful,  as  non-empirical  sciences,  seems  to  be  a  more 
difficult  question.  It  seems  clear,  for  instance,  that  ethical  discus- 
sions, such  as  bulk  so  largely  in  our  contemporary  literature,  as  to  what 
is  the  right  course  of  conduct  under  various  conditions,  are  concerned 
throughout  with  an  empirical  material,  namely,  the  existing  pecu- 
liarities of  human  nature  as  we  find  it,  and  must  therefore  be  regarded 
as  capable  only  of  an  empirical  and  therefore  problematic  solution. 
Accordingly  I  was  at  one  time  myself  tempted  to  regard  ethics  as 
a  purely  empirical  science,  and  even  published  a  lengthy  treatise 
in  defense  of  that  point  of  view  and  in  opposition  to  the  whole 
Kantian  conception  of  the  possibility  of  a  constructive  Metaphysik 
der  Sitten.  It  seems,  however,  possible  to  hold  that  in  the  question 
"What  do  we  mean  by  good?"  as  distinguished  from  the  question 
"  What  in  particular  is  it  right  to  do?  "  there  is  no  more  of  a  reference 
to  the  empirical  facts  of  human  psycholog}''  than  in  the  question 
"What  do  we  mean  by  truth?"  and  that  there  must  therefore  be 
a  non-empirical  answer  to  the  problem.  The  same  would  of  course 
hold  equally  true  of  the  question  "What  is  beauty?"  If  there  are, 
however,  such  a  pure  science  of  ethics  and  again  of  aesthetics,  it 
must  at  least  be  allowed  that  for  the  most  part  these  sciences  are 
still  undiscovered,  and  that  the  ethical  and  sesthetical  results  hitherto 
established  are  in  the  main  of  an  empirical  nature,  and  this  must 
be  my  excuse  for  confining  the  remarks  of  the  next  two  paragraphs 
to  the  two  great  pure  sciences  of  which  the  general  principles  may 
be  taken  to  be  now  in  large  measure  known. 

That  metaphysics  and  logic  should  sometimes  have  been  absolutely 
identified,  as  for  instance  by  Hegel,  will  not  surprise  us  when  we 
consider  how  hard  it  becomes  on  the  view  here  defended  to  draw  any 
hard  and  fast  boundary  fine  between  them.  For  metaphysics,  accord- 
ing to  this  conception  of  its  scope,  deals  with  the  formulation  of  the 
self-evident  principles  implied,  in  there  being  such  a  thing  as  truth 
and  the  deductions  which  these  principles  warrant  us  in  drawing. 


236  METAPHYSICS 

Thus  it  might  be  fairly  said  to  be  the  supreme  science  of  order,  and 
it  would  not  be  hard  to  show  that  all  the  special  questions  commonly 
included  in  its  range,  as  to  the  nature  of  space,  time,  causation,  con- 
tinuity, and  so  forth,  are  all  branches  of  the  general  question,  how 
many  types  of  order  among  concepts  are  there,  and  what  is  their 
nature.  A  completed  metaphysics  would  thus  appear  as  the  realiza- 
tion of  Plato's  splendid  conception  of  dialectic  as  the  ultimate  reduc- 
tion of  the  contents  of  knowledge  to  order  by  their  continuous  de- 
duction from  a  supreme  principle  (or,  we  may  add,  principles) .  Now 
such  a  view  seems  to  make  it  almost  impossible  to  draw  any  ulti- 
mate distinction  between  logic  and  metaphysics.  For  logic  is  strictly 
the  science  of  the  mutual  implication  of  propositions,  as  we  see  as 
soon  as  we  carefully  exclude  from  it  all  psychological  accretions.  In 
the  question  what  are  the  conditions  under  which  one  proposition 
or  group  of  propositions  imply  another,  we  exhaust  the  whole  scope 
of  logic  pure  and  proper,  as  distinguished  from  its  various  empirical 
applications.  This  is  the  important  point  which  is  so  commonly 
forgotten  when  logic  is  defined  as  being  in  some  way  a  study  of  "  psy- 
chical processes,"  or  when  the  reference  to  the  presence  of  "minds" 
in  which  propositions  exist,  is  intended  into  logical  science.  We  can- 
not too  strongly  insist  that  for  logic  the  question  so  constantly  raised 
in  a  multitude  of  text-books,  what  processes  actually  take  place  when 
we  pass  from  the  assertion  of  the  premises  to  the  assertion  of  the 
conclusion,  is  an  irrelevant  one,  and  that  the  only  logical  problem 
raised  by  inference  is  whether  the  assertion  of  the  premises  as  true 
warrants  the  further  assertion  of  the  conclusion,  supposing  it  to  be 
made.  (At  the  risk  of  a  little  digression  I  cannot  help  pointing  out  that 
the  confusion  between  a  logical  and  a  psychological  problem  is  com- 
mitted whenever  we  attempt,  as  is  so  often  done,  to  make  the  self- 
evidence  of  a  principle  identical  with  our  psychological  inability  to 
believe  the  contradictory.  From  the  strictly  logical  point  of  view, 
all  that  is  to  be  said  about  the  two  sides  of  such  an  ultimate  contra- 
diction is  that  the  one  is  true  and  the  other  is  false.  Whether  it  is 
or  is  not  possible,  as  a  matter  of  psychical  fact  for  me  to  affirm  with 
equal  conviction,  both  sides  of  a  contradiction,  knowing  that  I  am 
doing  so,  is  a  question  of  empirical  psychology  which  is  possibly 
insoluble,  and  at  any  rate  seems  not  to  have  received  from  the 
psychologists  the  attention  it  deserves.  But  the  logician,  so  far  as 
I  can  see,  has  no  interest  as  a  logician  in  its  solution.  For  him  it 
would  still  be  the  case  even  though  all  mankind  should  actually  and 
consciously  affirm  both  sides  of  a  given  contradiction,  that  one  of  the 
affirmations  would  be  true,  and  the  other  untrue.)  Logic  thus  seems 
to  become  either  the  whole  or  an  integral  part  of  the  science  of  order, 
and  there  remain  only  two  possible  ways  of  distinguishing  it  from 
metaphysics.    It  might  be  suggested  that  logical  order,  the  order  of 


METAPHYSICS  AND  THE  OTHER  SCIENCES       237 

implication  between  truths,  is  only  one  species  of  a  wider  genus, 
order  in  general  by  the  side,  for  example,  of  spatial,  temporal,  and 
numerical  order,  and  thus  that  logic  is  one  subordinate  branch  of 
the  wider  science  of  metaphysics.  Such  a  view,  of  course,  implies 
that  there  are  a  plurality  of  ultimately  independent  forms  of  order 
irreducible  to  a  single  type.  Whether  this  is  the  case,  I  must  confess 
myself  at  present  incompetent  to  decide,  though  the  signal  success 
with  which  the  principles  of  number  have  already  been  deduced 
from  the  fundamental  definitions  and  axioms  of  symbolic  logic,  and 
number  itself  defined,  as  by  Mr.  Russell,  in  terms  of  the  purely  logical 
concept  of  class-relation,  seems  to  afford  some  presumption  to  the 
contrary.  Or  it  may  be  held  that  the  difference  is  purely  one  of  the 
degree  of  completeness  with  which  the  inquiry  into  order  is  pursued. 
Thus  the  ordinary  symbolic  logic  of  what  Schroder  has  called  the 
"identical  calculus,"  or  "calculus  of  domains,"  consists  of  a  series 
of  deductions  from  the  fundamental  concepts  of  class  and  number, 
identical  equality,  totality  or  the  "logical  1,"  zero  or  the  null-class, 
and  the  three  principles  of  identity,  subsumption,  and  negation.  The 
moment  you  cease  to  accept  these  data  in  their  totality  as  the  given 
material  for  your  science,  and  to  inquire  into  their  mutual  coherence, 
by  asking  for  instance  whether  any  one  of  them  could  be  denied, 
and  yet  a  body  of  consistent  results  deduced  from  the  rest,  your 
inquiry,  it  might  be  said,  becomes  metaphysics.  So,  again,  the  dis- 
cussion of  the  well-known  contradictions  which  arise  when  we  try  to 
apply  these  principles  in  their  entirety  and  without  modification  to 
classes  of  classes  instead  of  classes  of  individuals,  or  of  the  problem 
raised  by  Peano  and  Russell,  whether  the  assertions  "Socrates  is 
a  man"  and  "the  Greeks  are  men"  affirm  the  same  or  a  different 
relation  between  their  subject  and  predicate  (which  seems  indeed  to 
be  the  same  question  differently  stated),  would  generally  be  allowed 
to  be  metaphysical.  And  the  same  thing  seems  to  be  equally  true 
of  the  introduction  of  time-relations  into  the  interpretation  of  our 
symbols  for  predication  employed  by  Boole  in  his  treatment  of 
hypotheticals,  and  subsequently  adopted  by  his  successors  as  the 
foundation  of  the  "calculus  of  equivalent  statements." 

However  we  may  decide  such  questions,  we  seem  at  least  driven 
by  their  existence  to  the  recognition  of  two  important  conclusions. 
(1)  The  relation  between  logical  and  metaphysical  problems  is  so  close 
that  you  cannot  in  consistency  deny  the  possibility  of  a  science  of 
metaphysics  unless  you  are  prepared  with  the  absolute  skeptic  to 
go  the  length  of  denying  the  possibility  of  logic  also,  and  reducing 
the  first  principles  of  inference  to  the  level  of  formulae  which  have 
happened  hitherto  to  prove  useful  but  are,  for  all  we  know,  just  as 
likely  to  fail  us  in  future  application  as  not.  (Any  appeal  to  the 
doctrine  of  chances  would  be  out  of  place  here,  as  that  doctrine  is 


238  METAPHYSICS 

itself  based  on  the  very  principles  at  stake.)  (2)  The  existence  of 
fundamental  problems  of  this  kind  which  remained  almost  or  wholly 
unsuspected  until  revealed  in  our  own  time  by  the  creation  of  a  science 
of  symbolic  logic  should  console  us  if  ever  we  are  tempted  to  suspect 
that  metaphysics  is  at  any  rate  a  science  in  which  all  the  main  con- 
structive work  has  already  been  accomplished  by  the  great  thinkers 
of  the  past.  To  me  it  appears,  on  the  contrary,  that  the  recent  enor- 
mous developments  in  the  purely  formal  sciences  of  logic  and  mathe- 
matics, with  the  host  of  fundamental  problems  they  open  up,  give 
promise  of  an  approaching  era  of  fresh  speculative  construction 
which  bids  fair  to  be  no  less  rich  in  results  than  any  of  the  great 
"golden"  periods  in  the  past  history  of  our  science.  Indeed,  but 
that  I  would  avoid  the  slightest  suspicion  of  a  desire  to  advertise 
personal  friends,  I  fancy  I  might  even  venture  to  name  some  of  those 
to  whom  we  may  reasonably  look  for  the  work  to  be  done. 

Of  the  relation  of  metaphysics  to  pure  mathematics  it  would  be 
impertinent  for  any  but  a  trained  mathematician  to  say  very  much. 
I  must  therefore  be  content  to  point  out  that  the  same  difficulty 
in  drawing  boundary  lines  meets  us  here  as  in  the  case  of  logic.  Not 
so  long  ago  this  difficulty  might  have  been  ignored,  as  it  still  is  by  too 
many  writers  on  the  philosophy  of  science.  Until  recently  mathematics 
would  have  been  thought  to  be  adequately  defined  as  the  science  of 
numerical  and  quantitative  relations,  and  adequatel}^  distinguished 
from  metaphysics  by  the  non-quantitative  and  non-numerical  char- 
acter of  the  latter,  though  it  would  probably  have  been  admitted  that 
the  problem  of  the  definition  of  quantity  and  number  themselves  is 
a  metaphysical  one.  But  in  the  present  state  of  our  knowledge  such 
an  account  seems  doubly  unsatisfactory.  On  the  one  hand,  we  have 
to  recognize  the  existence  of  branches  of  mathematics,  such  as  the 
so-called  descriptive  geometry,  which  are  neither  quantitative  nor 
numerical,  and,  on  the  other,  quantity  as  distinct  from  number  appears 
to  play  no  part  in  mathematical  science,  while  number  itself,  thanks 
to  the  labors  of  such  men  as  Cantor  and  Dedekind,  seems,  as  I  have 
said  before,  to  be  known  now  to  be  only  a  special  type  of  order  in 
a  series.  Thus  there  appears  to  be  ground  for  regarding  serial  order 
as  the  fundamental  category  of  mathematics,  and  we  are  thro-^oi  back 
once  more  upon  the  difficult  task  of  deciding  how  many  ultimately 
irreducible  types  of  order  there  may  be  before  we  can  undertake  any 
precise  discrimination  between  mathematical  and  metaphysical 
science.  Ho^^ever  we  may  regard  the  problem,  it  is  at  least  certain 
that  the  recent  researches  of  mathematicians  into  the  meaning  of 
such  concepts  as  continuity  and  infinity  have,  besides  opening  up  new 
metaphysical  problems,  done  much  to  transfigure  the  familiar  ones, 
as  all  readers  of  Professor  Royce  must  be  aware.  For  instance  I 
imagine  all  of  us  here  present,  even  the  youngest,  were  brought  up  on 


METAPHYSICS   AND  THE  OTHER  SCIENCES       239 

the  Aristotelian  doctrine  that  there  is  and  can  be  no  such  thing  as  an 
actually  existing  infinite  collection,  but  which  of  us  would  care  to 
defend  that  time-honored  position  to-day?  Similarly  with  continuity 
all  of  us  were  probably  once  on  a  time  instructed  that  whereas  "  quan- 
tity" is  continuous,  number  is  essentially  "discrete,"  and  is  indeed 
the  typical  instance  of  what  we  mean  by  the  non-continuous.  To-day 
we  know  that  it  is  in  the  number-series  that  we  have  our  one  certain 
and  familiar  instance  of  a  perfect  continuum.  Still  a  third  illustration 
of  the  transforming  light  which  is  thrown  upon  old  standing  meta- 
physical puzzles  by  the  increasing  formal  development  of  mathe- 
matics may  be  found  in  the  difficulties  attendant  upon  the  conception 
of  the  "infinitely  little,"  once  regarded  as  the  logical  foundation  of 
the  so-called  Differential  Calculus.  With  the  demonstration,  which 
may  be  found  in  Mr.  Russell's  important  work,  that  "infinitesimal," 
unlike  "infinite,"  is  a  purely  relative  term,  and  that  there  are  no 
infinitesimal  real  numbers,  the  supposed  logical  significance  of  the 
concept  seems  simply  to  disappear.  Instances  of  this  kind  could  easily 
be  multiplied  almost  indefinitely,  but  those  already  cited  should  be 
sufficient  to  show  how  important  are  the  metaphysical  results  which 
may  be  anticipated  from  contemporary  mathematical  research,  and 
how  grave  a  mistake  it  would  be  to  regard  existing  metaphysical  con- 
struction, e.  g.,  that  of  the  Hegelian  system,  as  adequate  in  principle 
to  the  present  state  of  our  organized  knowledge.  In  fact,  all  the  mate- 
rials for  a  new  Kategorienlehre,  which  may  be  to  the  knowledge  of  our 
day  what  Hegel's  Logic  was  to  that  of  eighty  years  ago,  appear  to  lie 
ready  to  hand  when  it  may  please  Providence  to  send  us  the  meta- 
physician who  knows  how  to  avail  himself  of  them.  The  proof,  given 
since  this  address  was  delivered,  by  E.  Zermelo,  that  every  assem- 
blage can  be  well  ordered,  is  an  even  more  startling  illustration  of 
the  remarks  in  the  text. 

It  remains  to  say  something  of  the  relation  of  metaphysical  specu- 
lation to  the  various  sciences  which  make  use  of  empirical  premises. 
On  this  topic  I  may  be  allowed  to  be  all  the  more  brief,  as  I  have  quite 
recently  expressed  my  views  at  fair  length  in  an  extended  treatise 
(Elements  of  Metaphysics,  Bks.  3  and  4),  and  have  nothing  of  conse- 
quence to  add  to  what  has  been  there  said.  The  empirical  sciences, 
as  previously  defined,  appear  to  fall  into  two  main  classes,  distin- 
guished by  a  difference  which  corresponds  to  that  often  taken  in  the 
past  as  the  criterion  by  which  science  is  to  be  separated  from  philo- 
sophy. We  may  study  the  facts  of  temporal  sequence  either  with  a 
view  to  the  actual  control  of  future  sequences  or  with  a  view  to 
detecting  under  the  sequence  some  coherent  purpose.  It  is  in  the 
former  way  that  we  deal  with  facts  in  mechanics,  for  instance,  or  in 
chemistry,  in  the  latter  that  we  treat  them  when  we  study  history  for 
the  purpose  of  gaining  insight  into  national  aims  and  character.   We 


240  METAPHYSICS 

may,  if  we  please,  with  Professor  Royce,  distinguish  the  two  attitudes 
toward  fact  as  the  attitude  respectively  of  description  and  of  appre- 
ciation or  evaluation.  Now  as  regards  the  descriptive  sciences,  the 
position  to  which,  as  I  believe,  metaphysicians  are  more  and  more 
tending  is  that  here  metaphysics  has,  strictly  speaking,  no  right  at  all 
to  interfere.  Just  because  of  the  absence  from  metaphysics  itself  of  all 
empirical  premises,  it  can  be  no  business  of  the  metaphysician  to 
determine  what  the  course  of  events  will  be  or  to  prescribe  to  the 
sciences  what  methods  and  hypotheses  they  shall  employ  in  the  work 
of  such  determination.  Within  these  sciences  any  and  every  hypothe- 
sis is  sufficiently  justified,  whatever  its  nature,  so  long  as  it  enables 
us  more  efficiently  than  any  other  to  perform  the  actual  task  of  calcu- 
lation and  prediction.  And  it  was  owing  to  neglect  of  this  caution 
that  the  Naturphilosophie  of  the  early  nineteenth  century  speedily  fell 
into  a  disrepute  fully  merited  by  its  ignorant  presumption.  As  regards 
the  physical  sciences,  the  metaphysician  has  indeed  by  this  time 
probably  learned  his  lesson.  We  are  not  likely  to-day  to  repeat  the 
mistake  of  supposing  that  it  is  for  us  as  metaphysicians  to  dictate 
what  shall  be  the  physicist's  or  chemist's  definition  of  matter  or  mass 
or  elementary  substance  or  energy,  or  how  he  shall  formulate  the 
laws  of  motion  or  of  chemical  composition.  Here,  at  any  rate,  we  can 
see  that  the  metaphysician's  work  is  done  when  his  analysis  has  made 
it  clear  that  we  are  dealing  with  no  self-evident  truths  such  as  the 
laws  of  number,  but  with  inductive,  and  therefore  problematic  and 
provisional  results  of  empirical  assumptions  as  to  the  course  of  facts, 
assumptions  made  not  because  of  their  inherent  necessity,  but  because 
of  their  practical  utility  for  the  special  task  of  calculation.  It  is  only 
when  such  empirical  assumptions  are  treated  as  self-evident  axioms, 
in  fact  when  mechanical  science  gives  itself  out  as  a  mechanistic 
philosophy,  that  the  metaphysician  obtains  a  right  to  speak,  and  then 
only  for  the  purpose  of  showing  by  analysis  that  the  presence  of  the 
empirical  postulates  which  is  characteristic  of  the  natural  sciences  of 
itself  excludes  their  erection  into  a  philosophy  of  first  principles. 

What  is  important  in  this  connection  is  that  we  should  recognize 
quite  clearly  that  psychology  stands  in  this  respect  on  precisely  the 
same  logical  footing  as  physics  or  chemistry.  It  is  tempting  to  sup- 
pose that  in  psychology,  at  any  rate,  we  are  dealing  throughout  with 
absolute  certainties,  realities  which  "consciousness"  apprehends  just 
as  they  are  without  any  of  that  artificial  selection  and  construction 
which,  as  we  are  beginning  to  see,  is  imposed  upon  the  study  of  physi- 
cal nature  by  the  limitations  of  our  purpose  of  submitting  the  course 
of  events  to  calculation  and  manipulation.  And  it  is  a  natural  conse- 
quence of  this  point  of  view  to  infer  that  since  psychology  deals 
directly  with  reahties,  it  must  be  taken  as  the  foundation  of  the  meta- 
physical constructions  which  aim  at  understanding  the  general  char- 


METAPHYSICS   AND   THE   OTHER  SCIENCES        241 

acter  of  the  real  as  such.  The  consequence,  indeed,  disappears  at  once 
if  the  views  maintained  in  this  address  as  to  the  intimate  relation  of 
metaphysics  and  logic,  and  the  radical  expulsion  from  logic  of  all 
discussion  of  mental  processes  as  such,  be  admitted.  But  it  is  still 
important  to  note  that  the  premises  from  which  the  conclusion  in 
question  was  drawn  are  themselves  false.  We  must  never  allow  our- 
selves to  forget  that,  as  the  ever-increasing  domination  of  psychology 
by  the  highly  artificial  methods  of  observation  and  experiment  intro- 
duced by  Fechner  and  Wundt  is  daily  making  more  apparent, 
psychology  itself,  like  physics,  deals  not  directly  with  the  concrete 
realities  of  individual  experience,  but  with  an  abstract  selected  from 
that  experience,  or  rather  a  set  of  artificial  symbols  only  partially 
corresponding  with  the  realities  symbolized,  and  devised  for  the  spe- 
cial object  of  submitting  the  realm  of  mental  sequences  to  mathemat- 
ical calculation.  We  might,  in  fact,  have  based  this  inference  upon 
the  single  reflection  that  every  psychological  "law"  is  obtained,  like 
physical  laws,  by  the  statistical  method  of  elimination  of  individual 
peculiarities,  and  the  taking  of  an  average  from  an  extended  series 
of  measurements.  For  this  very  reason,  no  psychological  law  can 
possibly  describe  the  unique  realities  of  individual  experience.  We 
have  in  psychology,  as  in  the  physical  sciences,  the  duty  of  suspecting 
exact  correspondence  between  the  single  case  and  the  general  "law" 
to  be  of  itself  proof  of  error  somewhere  in  the  course  of  our  computa- 
tion. These  views,  which  I  suppose  I  learned  in  the  first  instance  from 
Mr.  F.  H.  Bradley's  paper  called  A  Defence  of  Phenomenalism  in 
Psychology ,  may  now,  I  think,  be  taken  as  finally  established  beyond 
doubt  by  the  exhaustive  analysis  of  Professor  Miinsterberg's  Grund- 
zuge  der  Psychologic.  They  possess  the  double  advantage  of  freeing 
the  psychologist  once  for  all  from  any  interference  by  the  meta- 
physician in  the  prosecution  of  his  proper  study,  and  delivering 
metaphysics  from  the  danger  of  having  assumptions  whose  sole  justi- 
fication lies  in  their  utility  for  the  purpose  of  statistical  computation 
thrust  upon  it  as  self-evident  principles.  For  their  full  discussion  I 
may  perhaps  be  allowed  to  refer  to  the  first  three  chapters  of  the 
concluding  book  of  my  Elements  of  Metaphysics. 

When  we  turn  to  the  sciences  which  aim  at  the  appreciation  or 
evaluation  of  empirical  fact,  the  case  seems  rather  different.  It  may 
fairly  be  regarded  as  incumbent  on  the  metaphysician  to  consider 
how  far  the  general  conception  he  has  formed  of  the  character  of 
reality  can  be  substantiated  and  filled  in  by  our  empirical  knowledge 
of  the  actual  course  of  temporal  sequence.  And  thus  the  way  seems 
to  lie  open  to  the  construction  of  what  may  fairly  be  called  a  Philo- 
sophy of  Nature  and  History.  For  instance,  a  metaphysician  who  has 
rightly  or  wrongly  convinced  himself  that  the  universe  can  only  be 
coherently  conceived  as  a  society  of  souls  or  wills  may  reasonably  go 


242  METAPHYSICS 

on  to  ask  what  views  seem  best  in  accord  with  our  knowledge  of 
human  character  and  animal  intelligence  as  to  the  varying  degrees  of 
organized  intelligence  manifested  by  the  members  of  such  a  hierarchy 
of  souls,  and  the  nature  and  amount  of  mutual  intercourse  between 
them.  And  again,  he  may  fairly  ask  what  general  way  of  conceiving 
what  we  loosely  call  the  inanimate  world  would  at  once  be  true  to 
fundamental  metaphysical  principles  and  free  from  disagreement 
with  the  actual  state  of  our  physical  hypotheses.  Only  he  will  need  to 
bear  in  mind  that  since  conclusions  on  these  points  involve  appeal 
to  the  present  results  of  the  inductive  sciences,  and  thus  to  purely 
empirical  postulates,  any  views  he  may  adopt  must  of  necessity  share 
in  the  problematic  and  provisional  character  of  the  empirical  sciences 
themselves,  and  can  have  no  claim  to  be  regarded  as  definitely  de- 
monstrated in  respect  of  their  details.  I  will  here  only  indicate  very 
briefly  two  lines  of  inquiry  to  which  these  reflections  appear  appli- 
cable. The  growth  of  evolutionary  science,  with  the  new  light  it  has 
thrown  upon  the  processes  by  M^hich  useful  variations  may  be  estab- 
lished without  the  need  for  presupposing  conscious  preexisting  design, 
naturally  gives  rise  to  the  question  whether  such  unconscious  factors 
are  of  themselves  sufficient  to  account  for  the  actual  course  of  devel- 
opment so  far  as  it  can  be  traced,  or  whether  the  actual  history  of  the 
world  offers  instances  of  results  which,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  can  only 
have  issued  from  deliberate  design.  And  thus  we  seem  justified  in 
regarding  the  problem  of  the  presence  of  ends  in  Nature  as  an  intel- 
'ligible  and  legitimate  one  for  the  philosophy  of  the  future.  I  would 
only  suggest  that  such  an  inquiry  must  be  prosecuted  throughout  by 
the  same  empirical  methods,  and  with  the  same  consciousness  of  the 
provisional  character  of  any  conclusions  we  may  reach  which  would 
be  recognized  as  in  place  if  we  were  called  on  to  decide  whether  some 
peculiar  characteristic  of  an  animal  group  or  some  singular  social 
practice  in  a  recently  discovered  tribe  does  or  does  not  indicate 
definite  purpose  on  the  part  of  breeders  or  legislators. 

The  same  remarks,  in  my  opinion,  apply  to  the  familiar  problems 
of  Natural  Theology  relative  to  the  existence  and  activity  of  such 
non-human  intelligences  as  are  commonly  understood  by  the  names 
"  God  "  or  "  gods."  Hume  and  Kant,  as  it  seems  to  me,  have  definitely 
shown  between  them  that  the  old-fashioned  attempts  to  demonstrate 
from  self-evident  principles  the  existence  of  a  supreme  personal  intel- 
ligence as  a  condition  of  the  very  being  of  truth  all  involve  unavoid- 
able logical  paralogisms.  I  should  myself,  indeed,  be  prepared  to  go 
further,  and  to  say  that  the  conception  of  a  single  personality  as  the 
ground  of  truth  and  reality  can  be  demonstrated  to  involve  contra- 
diction, but  this  I  know  is  a  question  upon  which  some  philosophers 
for  whom  I  entertain  the  profoundest  respect  hold  a  contrary  opinion. 
The  more  modest  question,  however,  whether  the  actual  course  of 


METAPHYSICS  AND   THE  OTHER  SCIENCES       243 

human  history  affords  probable  ground  for  believing  in  the  activity 
of  one  or  more  non-human  personalities  as  agents  in  the  development 
of  our  species  I  cannot  but  think  a  perfectly  proper  subject  for 
empirical  investigation,  if  only  it  be  borne  in  mind  that  any  conclusion 
upon  such  a  point  is  inevitably  affected  by  the  provisional  character 
of  our  information  as  to  empirical  facts  themselves ,  and  can  claim  in 
consequence  nothing  more  than  a  certain  grade  of  probability.  With 
this  proviso,  I  cannot  but  regard  the  question  as  to  the  existence  of 
a  God  or  of  gods  as  one  upon  which  we  may  reasonably  hope  for 
greater  certainty  as  our  knowledge  of  the  empirical  facts  of  the 
world's  history  increases.  And  I  should  be  inclined  only  to  object  to 
any  attempt  to  foreclose  examination  by  forcing  a  conclusion  either 
in  the  theistic  or  in  the  atheistic  sense  on  alleged  grounds  of  a  priori 
metaphysics.  In  a  word,  I  would  maintain  not  only  with  Kant  that 
the  "  physico-theological  "  argument  is  specially  deserving  of  our 
regard,  but  with  Boole  that  it  is  with  it  that  Natural  Theology 
must  stand  or  fall. 

NOTE   ON   EXTENSION   AND    INTENSION   OF   TERMS 

Among  the  numerous  difficulties  which  beset  the  teaching  of  the 
elements  of  formal  logic  to  beginners,  one  of  the  earliest  is  that  of 
deciding  whether  all  names  shall  be  considered  to  have  meaning  both 
in  extension  and  intension.  As  we  all  know,  the  problem  arises  in 
connection  with  two  classes  of  names,  (1)  proper  names  of  individ- 
uals, (2)  abstract  terms.  I  should  like  to  indicate  what  seems  to  me 
the  true  solution  of  the  difficulty,  though  I  do  not  remember  to  have 
seen  it  advocated  anywhere  in  just  the  form  I  should  prefer. 

(1)  As  to  proper  names.  It  seems  clear  that  those  who  regard  the 
true  proper  name  as  a  meaningless  label  are  nearer  the  truth  than 
those  who  assert  with  Jevons  that  a  proper  name  has  for  its  intension 
all  the  predicates  which  can  be  truly  ascribed  to  the  object  named. 
As  has  often  been  observed,  it  is  a  sufficient  proof  that,  for  example, 
John  does  not  mean  "  a  human  being  of  the  male  sex,"  to  note  that  he 
who  names  his  daughter,  his  dog,  or  his  canoe  John,  makes  no  false 
assertion,  though  he  may  commit  a  solecism.  So  far  the  followers  of 
Mill  seem  to  have  a  satisfactory  answer  to  Jevons,  when  they  say,  for 
example,  that  he  confuses  the  intension  of  a  term  with  its  accidental  or 
acquired  associations.  (So,  again,  we  can  see  that  Socrates  cannot 
mean  "the  wisest  of  the  Greek  philosophers,"  by  considering  that  I 
may  perfectly  well  understand  the  statement  "there  goes  Socrates" 
without  being  aware  that  Socrates  is  wise  or  a  Greek  or  a  philosopher.) 
And  if  we  objected  that  no  proper  name  actually  in  use  is  ever  with- 
out some  associations  which  in  part  determine  its  meaning  by  restrict- 
ing its  applicability,  it  would  be  a  valid  rejoinder  that  in. pure  logic 
we  have  to  consider  not  the  actual  usages  of  language,  but  those  that 


244  METAPHYSICS 

would  prevail  in  an  ideal  language  purged  of  all  elements  of  irre- 
levancy. In  such  an  ideal  scientific  language,  it  might  be  said,  the 
proper  name  would  be  reduced  to  the  level  of  a  mere  mark  serviceable 
for  identification,  but  conveying  no  implication  whatever  as  to  the 
special  nature  of  the  thing  identified.  Thus  it  would  be  indifferent 
what  mark  we  attach  to  any  particular  individual,  just  as  in  mathe- 
matics it  is  indifferent  what  alphabetical  symbol  we  appropriate  to 
stand  for  a  given  class  or  number.  I  think,  however,  that  even  in  such 
an  ideal  scientific  language  the  proper  name  would  have  a  certain 
intension.  In  the  first  place,  the  use  of  proper  name  seems  to  inform 
us  that  the  thing  named  is  not  unique,  is  not  the  only  member  of 
a  class.  To  a  monotheist,  for  instance,  the  name  "God"  is  no  true 
proper  name,  nor  can  he  consistently  give  a  proper  name  to  his 
Deity.  It  is  only  where  one  member  of  a  class  has  to  be  distinguished 
from  others  that  the  bestowal  of  a  proper  name  has  a  meaning. 
And,  further,  to  give  a  thing  a  proper  name  seems  to  imply  that  the 
thing  is  itself  not  a  class.  In  logic  we  have,  of  course,  occasion  to  form 
the  concept  of  classes  which  have  other  classes  for  their  individual 
members.  But  the  classes  which  compose  such  classes  of  classes  could 
not  themselves  be  identified  by  means  of  proper  names.  Thus  the 
employment  of  a  proper  name  seems  to  indicate  that  the  thing 
named  is  not  the  only  member  of  its  class,  and  further  that  it  is  not 
itself  a  class  of  individuals.  Beyond  this  it  seems  to  be  a  mere  question 
of  linguistic  convention  what  information  the  use  of  a  proper  name 
shall  convey.  Hence  it  ought  to  be  said,  not  that  the  proper  name  has 
no  intension,  but  that  it  represents  a  limiting  case  in  which  intension 
is  at  a  minimum. 

(2)  As  to  abstract  terms.  Ought  we  to  say,  with  so  many  English 
formal  logicians,  that  an  abstract  term  is  always  singular  and  non- 
intensional?  The  case  for  asserting  that  such  terms  are  all  singular, 
I  own,  seems  unanswerable.  For  it  is  clear  that  if  the  name  of  an 
attribute  or  relation  is  equally  the  name  of  another  attribute  or  rela- 
tion, it  is  ambiguous  and  thus  not  properly  one  term  at  all.  To  say,  for 
example,  that  whiteness  means  two  or  more  distinct  qualities  seems 
to  amount  to  saying  that  it  has  no  one  definite  meaning.  Of  course,  it 
is  true  that  milk  is  white,  paper  is  white,  and  snow  is  white,  and  yet 
the  color-tones  of  the  three  are  distinct.  But  what  we  assert  here  is, 
not  that  there  are  different  whitenesses,  but  only  that  there  are  differ- 
ent degrees  of  approximation  to  a  single  ideal  standard  or  type  of 
whiteness.  It  is  just  because  the  whiteness  we  have  in  view  is  one  and 
not  many  that  we  can  intelligibly  assert,  for  example,  that  newly 
fallen  snow  is  whiter  than  any  paper.  All  the  instances  produced  by 
Mill  to  show  that  abstract  terms  may  be  general  seem  to  me  either  to 
involve  confusion  between  difference  of  kind  and  difference  in  degree 
of  approximation  to  type,  or  else  to  depend  upon  treating  as  abstract 


METAPHYSI€S   AND   THE   OTHER   SCIENCES        245 

a  term  which  is  really  concrete.  Thus  when  we  say  red,  blue,  green, 
are  different  kinds  of  color,  surely  what  we  mean  is  different  kinds  of 
colored  surface.  Qua  colored,  they  are  not  different;  I  mean  just  as 
much  and  no  more  when  I  say  "a  red  thing  is  colored,"  or  "has 
color,"  as  when  I  say  "  a  green  thing  is  colored."  If  Mill  were  right,  the 
proposition  "red  is  a  color"  ought  to  mean  exactly  the  same  as  "red 
is  red."  Or,  to  put  it  in  another  way,  it  would  become  impossible  to 
form  in  thought  any  concept  of  a  single  class  of  colored  things. 

But  need  we  infer  because  abstract  terms  are  singular  that  there- 
fore they  have  no  intension  and  are  mere  meaningless  marks?  Com- 
monly as  this  inference  is  made,  it  seems  to  me  clearly  mistaken.  It 
seems,  in  fact,  to  rest  upon  the  vague  and  ill-defined  principle  that 
an  attribute  can  have  no  attributes  of  its  own.  That  it  is  false  is 
shown,  I  think,  by  the  simple  reflection  that  scientific  definitions 
are  one  and  all  statements  as  to  the  meaning  of  abstract  names  of 
attributes  and  relations.  For  example,  the  definition  of  a  circle  is 
a  statement  as  to  the  meaning  of  circularity,  the  legal  definition  of 
responsible  persons  a  statement  as  to  the  meaning  of  the  abstraction 
"responsibility,"  and  so  on.  (We  only  evade  the  point  if  we  argue 
that  abstract  terms  when  used  as  the  subjects  of  propositions  are 
really  being  employed  concretely.  For  "cruelty  is  odious,"  for 
instance,  does  not  merely  mean  that  cruel  acts  are  odious  acts, 
but  that  they  are  odious  because  they  are  cruel.)  In  fact,  the  doc- 
trine that  abstract  terms  have  no  intension  would  seem,  if  thought 
out,  to  lead  to  the  view  that  there  are  only  classes  of  individuals,  but 
no  classes  of  classes.  Thus  to  say  "cruel  acts  are  odious  because 
cruel "  implies,  not  only  that  I  can  form  the  concept  of  a  class  of  cruel 
acts,  but  also  that  of  classes  of  odious  acts  of  which  the  class  of  cruel 
acts  in  its  turn  is  a  member.  And  to  admit  as  much  as  this  is  to  admit 
that  the  class  of  cruel  acts,  considered  as  a  member  of  the  class  of  odious 
acts,  shares  the  common  predicate  of  odiousness  with  the  other  classes 
of  acts  composing  the  higher  class.  Hence  the  true  account  of  abstract 
terms  seems  to  me  to  be  that  we  have  in  them  another  limiting  case, 
a  case  in  which  the  extension  and  the  intension  are  coincident.  Inci- 
dentally, by  illustrating  the  ambiguity  of  the  principle  that  attributes 
have  no  attributes  of  their  own,  our  discussion  seems  to  indicate  the 
advantage  of  taking  the  purely  extensional  view  as  opposed  to  the 
predicative  view  of  the  import  of  propositions  as  the  basis  of  an  ele- 
mentary treatment  of  logical  doctrine. 


THE  PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  METAPHYSICS  ' 

BY   ALEXANDER   T.    ORMOND 

[Alexander  Thomas  Ormond,  McCosh  Professor  of  Philosophy,  Princeton 
University,  since  1897.  b.  1847,  Punxsutawney,  Pennsylvania.  Mental 
Science  Fellow,  Princeton,  1877-78;  Post-grad.  Bonn  and"  Berhn,  1884^85; 
Ph.D.  Princeton,  1880;  A.B.  ibid.  1877;  LL.D.  Miami,  1899.  Professor  of 
Philosophy  and  History,  University  of  Minnesota,  1880-83;  Professor  of 
Mental  Science  and  Logic,  Princeton  University,  1883-97.  Member  Ameri- 
can Philosophical  Association,  American  Psychological  Association.] 

I 

THE    PRELIMINARY    QUESTION 

The  living  problems  of  any  science  arise  out  of  two  sources:  (1)  out 
of  what  men  may  think  of  it,  in  view  of  its  nature  and  claims,  and 
(2)  the  problems  that  at  any  period  are  vital  to  it,  and  in  the  solution 
of  which  it  realizes  the  purpose  of  its  existence.  Now  if  we  distinguish 
the  body  of  the  sciences  which  deal  with  aspects  of  the  world's  phenom- 
ena— and  here  I  would  include  both  the  psychic  and  the  physical  — 
from  metaphysics,  which  professes  to  go  behind  the  phenomenon  and 
determine  the  world  in  terms  of  its  inner,  and,  therefore,  ultimate  real- 
ity, it  may  be  truly  said  of  the  body  of  the  sciences  that  they  are  in  a 
position  to  disregard  in  a  great  measure  questions  that  arise  out  of  the 
first  source,  inasmuch  as  the  data  from  which  they  make  their  de- 
parture are  obvious  to  common  observation.  Our  world  is  all  around 
us,  and  its  phenomena  either  press  upon  us  or  are  patent  to  our 
observation.  Lying  thus  within  the  field  of  observation,  it  does 
not  occur  to  the  average  mind  to  question  either  the  legitimacy  or 
the  possibility  of  that  effort  of  reflection  which  is  devoted  to  their 
investigation  and  interpretation.  Metaphysics,  however,  enjoys  no 
such  immunity  as  this,  but  its  claims  are  liable  to  be  met  with  skep- 
ticism or  denial  at  the  outset,  and  this  is  due  partly  to  the  nature  of 
its  initial  claims,  and  partly  to  the  fact  that  its  real  data  are  less  open 
to  observation  than  are  those  of  the  sciences.  I  say  partly  to  the 
nature  of  the  initial  claims  of  metaphysics,  for  it  is  characteristic  of 
metaphysics  that  it  refuses  to  regard  the  distinction  between  phe- 
nomena and  ground  or  inner  nature,  on  which  the  sciences  rest,  as 
final,  and  is  committed  from  the  outset  to  the  claim  that  the  real  is 
in  its  inner  nature  one  and  to  be  interpreted  in  the  light  of,  or  in 
terms  of,  its  inner  unity;  whereas,  science  has  so  indoctrinated  the 
modern  mind  with  the  supposition  that  only  the  outer  movements 
of  things  are  open  to  knowledge,  while  their  inner  and  real  nature 
must  forever  remain  inaccessible  to  our  powers;  I  say  that  the  mod- 


THE  PRESENT  PROBLEMS   OF   METAPHYSICS     247 

ern  mind  has  been  so  imbued  with  this  pretension  as  to  have  almost 
completely  forgotten  the  fact  that  the  distinction  of  phenomenon 
and  ground  is  one  of  science's  own  making.  Neither  the  plain  man 
nor  the  cultured  man,  if  he  happens  not  to  be  tinctured  with  science, 
finds  his  world  a  duality.  The  things  he  deals  with  are  the  realities, 
and  it  is  only  when  his  naive  realism  begins  to  break  down  before 
the  complex  demands  of  his  growing  life,  that  the  thought  occurs  to 
him  that  his  world  may  be  more  complex  than  he  has  dreamed.  It  is 
clear,  then,  that  the  distinction  of  our  world  into  phenomena  and 
ground,  on  which  science  so  largely  rests,  is  a  first  product  of  reflec- 
tion, and  not  a  fact  of  observation  at  all. 

If  this  be  the  case,  it  may  be  possible  and  even  necessary  for 
reflection  at  some  stage  to  transcend  this  distinction.  At  least,  there 
can  be  no  reason  except  an  arbitrary  one  for  taking  this  first  step  of 
reflection  to  be  a  finality.  And  there  would  be  the  same  justification 
for  a  second  step  that  would  transcend  this  dualism,  as  for  the  initial 
step  out  of  which  the  distinction  arose;  provided,  it  should  be  found 
that  the  initial  distinction  does  not  supply  an  adequate  basis  for  a 
rational  interpretation  of  the  world  that  can  be  taken  as  final.  Now, 
it  is  precisely  because  the  dualistic  distinction  of  the  sciences  does  fail 
in  this  regard,  that  a  further  demand  for  a  reflective  transformation 
of  the  data  arises.  Let  us  bear  in  mind  that  the  data  of  the  sciences 
are  not  the  simple  facts  of  observation,  but  rather  those  facts  trans- 
formed by  an  act  of  reflection  by  virtue  of  which  they  become  phe- 
nomena distinguished  from  a  more  fundamental  nature  on  which 
they  depend  and  which  itself  is  not  open  to  observation.  The  real 
data  of  science  are  found  only  when  the  world  of  observation  has  been 
thus  transformed  by  an  act  of  reflection.  If  then  at  some  stage  in  our 
effort  to  interpret  our  world  it  should  become  clear  that  the  sciences 
of  phenomena,  whatever  value  their  results  may  possess,  are  not  giv- 
ing us  an  interpretation  in  terms  that  can  be  taken  as  final,  and  that  in 
order  to  ground  such  an  interpretation  a  further  transformation  of  our 
data  becomes  necessary,  I  do  not  see  why  any  of  the  sciences  should 
feel  that  they  have  cause  to  demur.  In  truth,  it  is  out  of  Just  such  a 
situation  as  this  that  the  metaphysical  interpretation  arises  (as  I 
propose  very  briefly  here  to  show) ,  a  situation  that  supplies  a  genuine 
demand  in  the  light  of  which  the  effort  of  metaphysics  to  understand 
its  world  seems  to  possess  as  high  a  claim  to  legitimacy  as  that  of  the 
sciences  of  phenomena.  Let  us  take  our  stand  with  the  plain  man  or 
the  child,  within  the  world  of  unmodified  observation.  The  things 
of  observation,  in  this  world,  are  the  realities,  and  at  first  we  may 
suppose  have  undergone  little  reflective  transformation.  The  first  re- 
fiective  effort  to  change  this  world  in  any  way  will,  no  doubt,  be  an 
effort  to  number  or  count  the  things  that  present  themselves  to  observa- 
tion, and  out  of  this  effort  will  arise  the  transformation  of  the  world 


248  METAPHYSICS 

that  results  from  considering  it  under  the  concepts  and  categories 
of  number.  In  short,  to  mathematical  reflection  of  this  simple  sort, 
the  things  of  observation  will  resolve  themselves  into  a  plurality  of 
countable  things,  which  the  numbering  reflection  becoming  explicit 
in  its  ordinal  and  cardinal  moments  will  translate  into  a  system  that 
will  be  regarded  as  a  whole  made  up  of  the  sum  of  its  parts.  The  very 
first  step,  then,  in  the  reflective  transformation  of  things  resolves 
them  into  a  dual  system,  the  world  conceived  as  a  cardinal  whole  that 
is  made  up  of  its  ordinal  parts,  and  exactly  equal  to  them.  This 
mathematical  conception  is  moreover  purely  quantitative;  involving 
the  exact  and  stable  equivalence  of  its  parts  or  units  and  that  of  the 
sum  of  the  parts  with  the  whole.  Now  it  is  with  this  purely  quantita- 
tive transformation  that  mathematics  and  the  mathematical  sciences 
begin.  We  may  ask,  then,  why  should *there  be  any  other  than  mathe- 
matical science,^  and  what  ground  can  non-mathematical  science  point 
to  as  substantiating  its  claims?  I  confess  I  can  see  no  other  final 
reason  than  this,  that  mathematical  science  does  not  meet  the  whole 
demand  we  feel  obliged  to  make  on  our  world.  If  mathematics  were 
asked  to  vindicate  itself,  it  no  doubt  would  do  so  by  claiming  that 
things  present  quantitative  aspects  on  which  it  founds  its  procedure. 
In  like  manner  non-mathematical,  or,  as  we  may  call  it,  physical  or 
natural  science,  will  seek  to  substantiate  its  claims  by  pointing  to 
certain  ultra-quantitative  or  qualitative  aspects  of  things.  It  is  true 
that,  so  far  as  things  are  merely  numerable,  they  are  purely  quantita- 
tive ;  but  mathematics  abstracts  from  the  content  and  character  of  its 
units  and  aggregates,  which  may  and  do  change,  so  that  a  relation 
of  stable  equivalence  is  not  maintained  among  them.  In  fact,  the 
basis  of  these  sciences  is  found  in  the  tendency  of  things  to  be  always 
changing  and  becoming  different  from  what  they  were  before.  The 
problem  of  these  sciences  is  how  to  ground  a  rational  scheme  of  know- 
ledge in  connection  with  a  fickle  world  like  that  of  qualitative  change. 
It  is  here  that  reflection  finds  its  problem,  and  noticing  that  the  tend- 
ency of  this  world  of  change  is  for  a  to  pass  into  b  and  thus  to  lose 
its  own  identity,  the  act  of  reflection  that  rationalizes  the  situation  is 
one  that  connects  a  and  b  by  relating  them  to  a  common  ground  x  of 
which  they  stand  as  successive  manifestations  or  symbols.  X  thus 
supplies  the  thread  of  identity  that  binds  the  two  changes  a  and  b  into 
a  relation  to  which  the  name  causation  may  be  applied.  And  just  as 
quantitative  equivalence  is  the  principle  of  relationship  among  the 
parts  of  the  simple  mathematical  world,  so  here  in  the  world  of  the 
dynamic  or  natural  sciences,  the  principle  of  relation  is  natural 
causation. 2  We  find,  then,  that  the  non-mathematical  sciences  rest  on 

1  I  do  not  raise  the  question  of  qualitative  mathematics  at  all.   It  is  clear  that 
the  first  mathematical  reflection  will  be  quantitative. 

2  By  natural  causation  I  mean  such  a  relationship  between  a  and  6  in  a  phenom- 
enal system  as  enables  a  through  its  connection  with  its  ground  to  determine  b. 


THE   PRESENT   PROBLEMS   OF   METAPHYSICS      249 

a  basis  that  is  constituted  by  a  second  act  of  reflection  ;  one  that 
translates  our  world  into  a  system  of  phenomena  causally  inter-related 
and  connected  with  their  underlying  grounds. 

We  have  now  reached  a  point  where  it  will  be  possible  in  a  few 
sentences  to  indicate  the  rise  of  the  metaphysical  reflection  and  the 
ground  on  which  it  rests.  If  we  consider  both  the  mathematical  and 
the  physical  ways  of  looking  at  things,  we  will  find  that  they  possess 
this  feature  in  common, — they  are  purely  external,  having  nothing 
to  say  respecting  the  inner  and,  therefore,  real  nature  of  the  things 
with  which  they  deal.  Or,  if  we  concede  the  latest  claims  of  some  of 
the  physical  speculators  and  agree  that  the  aim  of  physics  is  an 
ultimate  physical  explanation  of  reality,  it  will  still  be  true  that  the 
whole  standpoint  of  this  explanation  will  be  external.  Let  me  explain 
briefly  what  I  mean  substantially  by  the  term  external  as  I  use  it  here. 
Every  interpretation  of  a  world  is  a  function  of  some  knowing  con- 
sciousness, and  consequently  of  some  knowing  self.  This  is  too  obvious 
to  need  proof.  A  system  will  be  external  to  such  a  knower  just  to  the 
extent  that  the  knower  finds  it  dominated  and  determined  by  cate- 
gories that  are  different  from  those  of  its  own  determination.  A  world 
physically  interpreted  is  one  that  is  brought  completely  under  the 
rubrics  of  physics  and  mathematics;  whose  movements  yield  them- 
selves completely,  therefore,  to  a  mechanical  calculus  that  gives  rise 
to  purely  descriptive  formulae;  or  to  the  control  of  a  dynamic  prin- 
ciple; that  of  natural  causation,  by  virtue  of  which  everything  is 
determined  without  thought  of  its  own,  by  the  impulse  of  another, 
which  impulse  itself  is  not  directly  traceable  to  any  thought  or  pur- 
pose. Now,  the  occasion  for  the  metaphysical  reflection  arises  when 
this  situation  that  brings  us  face  to  face  with,  nay,  makes  us  part 
and  parcel  of,  an  alien  system  of  things,  becomes  intolerable,  and  the 
knower  begins  to  demand  a  closer  kinship  with  his  world.  The  knower 
finds  the  categories  of  his  own  central  and  characteristic  activity  in 
experience.  Here  he  is  conscious  of  being  an  agent  going  out  in  forms 
of  activity  for  the  realization  of  his  world.  The  determining  categories 
of  the  activity  he  is  most  fully  conscious  of,  are  interest,  idea,  previ- 
sion, purpose,  and  that  selective  activity  which  goes  to  its  termina- 
tion in  some  achieved  end.  The  metaphysical  interpretation  arises  out 
of  the  demand  that  the  world  shall  be  brought  into  bonds  of  kinship 
with  the  knower.  And  this  is  effected  by  generalizing  the  categories 
of  consciousness  and  applying  them  as  principles  of  interpretation  to 
the  world.  The  act  of  reflection  on  which  the  metaphysical  interpre- 
tation proceeds  is  one',  then,  in  which  the  world  of  science  is  further 
transformed  by  bringing  the  inner  nature  of  things  out  of  its  isolation 
and  translating  the  world-movements  into  process  the  terms  of  which 
are  no  longer  phenomena  and  hidden  ground,  but  rather  inception  and 
realization,  or,  more  specifically.  Idea  and  Reality.   And  the  point  to 


250  METAPHYSICS 

be  noted  here  is  the  fact  that  these  metaphysical  categories  are  led 
up  to  positivity  by  an  act  of  reflection  that  has  for  its  guiding  aim  an 
interpretation  of  the  world  that  will  be  more  ultimately  satisfactory 
to  the  knower  than  that  of  the  physical  or  natural  sciences;  while 
negatively,  it  is  led  up  to  by  the  refusal  of  the  knowing  consciousness 
to  rest  in  a  world  alien  to  its  own  nature  and  in  which  it  is  subordin- 
ated to  the  physical  and  made  a  mere  epiphenomenon. 

II 

QUESTIONS    OF    POINT    OF    VIEW,    PRINCIPLE    AND    METHOD    OF 
METAPHYSICS 

It  is  clear  from  what  has  been  said  that  the  metaphysical  inter- 
pretation proceeds  on  a  presupposition  radically  different  from  that 
of  mathematical  and  physical  science.  The  presumption  of  these 
sciences  is  that  the  world  is  physical,  that  the  physical  categories 
supply  the  norms  of  reality,  and  that  consciousness  and  the  psychic, 
in  general,  are  subordinate  and  phenomenal  to  the  physical.  On  the 
contrary,  metaphysics  arises  out  of  a  revolt  from  these  presumptions 
toward  the  opposite  presumption,  namely,  that  consciousness  itself 
is  the  great  reality,  and  that  the  norms  of  an  ultimate  interpretation  of 
things  are  to  be  sought  in  its  categories.  This  is  the  great  transfor- 
mation that  conditions  the  possibility  and  value  of  all  metaphysics. 
It  is  the  Copernican  revolution  which  the  mind  must  pass  through, 
a  revolution  in  which  matter  and  the  physical  world  yields  the 
primacy  to  mind;  a  revolution  in  which  consciousness  becomes  cen- 
tral, its  categories  and  analogies  supplying  the  principles  of  final 
world-interpretation.  Let  us  consider  then,  in  the  light  of  this  great 
Copernican  revolution,  the  questions  of  the  point  of  view,  principle, 
and  method  of  metaphysics.  And  here  the  utmost  brevity  must  be 
observed.  If  consciousness  be  the  great  reality,  then  its  own  central 
activity,  that  effort  by  which  it  realizes  its  world,  will  determine  for 
us  the  point  of  view  or  departure  of  which  we  are  in  quest.  This  will 
be  inner  rather  than  outer  ;  it  will  be  motived  by  interest,  will  shape 
itself  into  interest-directed  effort.  This  effort  will  be  cognitive;  dom- 
inated by  an  idea  which  will  be  an  anticipation  of  the  goal  of  the 
effort.  It  will,  therefore,  become  directive,  selective,  and  will  stand 
as  the  end  or  aim  of  the  completed  effort.  The  whole  movement  will 
thus  take  the  form,  genetically,  of  a  developing  purpose  informed  by 
an  idea,  or  teleologically ,  of  a  purpose  going  on  to  its  fulfillment  in  some 
aim  which  is  also  its  motive.  Now,  metaphysics  determines  its  point 
of  view  in  the  following  reasoning:  if  in  consciousness  we  find  the 
type  of  the  inner  nature  of  things,  then  the  point  of  view  for  the  inter- 
pretation of  this  inner  nature  will  be  to  seek  by  generalizing  the 
standpoint  of  consciously  determined  effort  and  asserting  that  this 


THE   PRESENT  PROBLEMS   OF  METAPHYSICS      251 

is  the  true  point  of  view  from  which  the  meaning  of  the  world  is  to  be 
sought. 

Having  determined  the  metaphysical  point  of  view,  the  next  ques- 
tion of  vital  importance  is  that  of  its  principle.  And  we  may  cut  mat- 
ters short  here  by  saying  at  once  that  the  principle  we  are  seeking  is 
that  of  sufficient  reason,  and  we  may  say  that  a  reason  will  be  suffi- 
cient when  it  adequately  expresses  the  world- view  or  concept  luider 
which  an  investigation  is  being  prosecuted.  Let  us  suppose  that  this 
world-view  is  that  of  simple  mathematics,  the  principle  of  sufficient 
reason  here  will  be  that  of  quantitative  equivalence  of  parts;  or,  from 
the  standpoint  of  the  whole,  that  of  infinite  divisibility.  Whereas,  if  we 
take  the  world  of  the  ultra-mathematical  science,  which  is  determined 
by  the  notion  of  phenomena  depending  on  underlying  ground,  we  will 
find  that  the  sufficient  reason  in  this  sphere  takes  the  form  of  adequate 
cause  or  condition.  The  determining  condition  or  causes  of  any  phys- 
ical phenomenon  supply,  from  that  point  of  view,  the  ratio  sufiidens 
of  its  existence.  We  have  seen  that  the  sufficiency  of  a  reason  in  the 
above  cases  has  been  determined  in  view  of  that  notion  which  defines 
the  kind  of  world  the  investigation  is  dealing  with.  Let  us  apply  this 
insight  to  the  problem  of  the  principle  of  metaphysics,  and  we  will 
soon  conclude  that  no  reason  can  be  metaphysically  sufficient  that 
does  not  satisfy  the  requirements  of  a  world  conceived  under  the 
notion  of  inception  and  realization  ;  or,  more  specifically,  idea  and 
reality.  In  short,  the  reason  of  metaphysics  will  refuse  to  regard  its 
world  as  a  mechanism  that  is  devoid  of  thought  and  intention;  that 
lacks,  in  short,  the  motives  of  internal  determination  and  movement, 
and  will  in  all  cases  insist  that  an  explanation  or  interpretation  can 
be  metaphysically  adequate  only  when  its  ultimate  reference  is  to  an 
idea  that  is  in  the  process  of  purposive  fulffilment.  Such  an  explana- 
tion we  call  teleological  or  rational,  rather  than  merely  mechanical, 
and  such  a  principle  is  alone  adequate  to  embody  the  ratio  suffidens 
of  metaphysics. 

Having  determined  the  point  of  view  and  principle  of  meta- 
physics, the  question  of  metaphysical  method  will  be  divested  of  some 
of  its  greatest  difficulties.  It  will  be  clear  to  any  one  who  reflects  that 
the  very  first  problem  in  regard  to  the  method  of  metaphysics  will 
be  that  of  its  starting-point  and  the  kind  of  results  it  is  to  look  for. 
And  little  can  be  accomplished  here  until  it  has  been  settled  that  con- 
sciousness is  to  have  the  primacy,  and  that  its  prerogative,  is  to  supply 
both  standpoint  and  principle  of  the  investigation.  We  have  gone 
a  long  way  toward  mastering  our  method  when  we  have  settled  these 
points:    (1)  that  the  metaphysical  world  is  a  world  of  consciousness; 

(2)  that  the  conscious  form  of  effort  rather  than  the  mechanical  is 
the  species  of  activity  or  movement  with  which  we  have  to  deal;  and, 

(3)  that  the  world  it  is  seeking  to  interpret  is  ultimately  one  of  idea 


252  METAPHYSICS 

and  reality  in  which  the  processes  take  the  purposive  form.  In  view  of 
this,  the  important  steps  of  method  (and  we  use  the  term  method  here 
in  the  most  fundamental  sense)  will  be  (1)  the  question  of  the  form  of 
metaphysical  activity  or  agency  as  contrasted  with  that  of  the  phys- 
ical sciences.  This  may  be  brought  out  in  the  contrast  of  the  two 
terms  finality  and  mere  efficiency,  in  which  by  mere  efficiency  is 
meant  an  agency  that  is  presumed  to  be  thoughtless  and  purposeless, 
and  consequently  without  foresight.  All  this  is  embodied  in  the  term 
force  or  physical  energy,  and  less  explicitly  in  that  of  natural  causa- 
tion. Contrasted  with  this,  finality  is  a  term  that  involves  the  for- 
ward impulse  of  idea,  prevision,  and  purpose.  Anything  that  is  cap- 
able of  any  sort  of  foretaste  has  in  it  a  principle  of  prevision,  selection, 
choice,  and  purpose.  The  impulse  that  motives  and  runs  it,  that  also 
stands  out  as  the  end  of  its  fulfillment,  is  a  foretaste,  an  Ahnung,  an 
anticipation,  and  the  whole  process  or  movement,  as  well  as  every 
part  of  it,  will  take  on  this  character.  (2)  The  second  question  of 
method  will  be  that  of  the  nature  of  this  category  of  which  finality 
is  the  form.  What  is  its  content,  pure  idea  or  pure  will,  or  a  synthesis 
that  includes  both?  We  have  here  the  three  alternatives  of  pure 
rationalism,  voluntarism,  and  a  doctrine  hard  to  characterize  in  a 
single  word;  that  rests  on  a  synthesis  of  the  norms  of  both  rational- 
ism and  voluntarism.  Without  debating  these  alternatives,  I  propose 
here  briefly  to  characterize  the  synthetic  concept  as  supplying  what 
I  conceive  to  be  the  most  satisfactory  doctrine.  The  principle  of  pure 
rationalism  is  one  of  insight  but  is  lacking  in  practical  energy, 
whereas,  that  of  voluntarism  supplies  practical  energy,  but  is  lacking 
in  insight.  Pure  voluntarism  is  blind,  whSie  pure  rationalism  is  power- 
less. But  the  synthesis  of  idea  and  will,  provided  we  go  a  step  further 
(as  I  think  we  must)  and  presuppose  also  a  germ  of  feeling  as  interest, 
supplies  both  insight  and  energy.  So  that  the  spring  out  of  which  our 
world  is  to  arise  may  be  described  as  either  the  idea  informed  with 
purposive  energy,  or  purpose  or  will  informed  and  guided  by  the  idea.  It 
makes  no  difference  which  form  of  conception  we  use.  In  either  case 
if  we  include  feeling  as  interest  we  are  able  to  conceive  movements 
originating  in  some  species  of  apprehension,  taking  the  dynamic 
form  of  purpose,  and  motived  and  selected,  so  to  speak,  by  interest; 
and  in  describing  such  activity  we  are  simply  describing  these  normal 
movements  of  consciousness  with  which  our  experience  makes  us 
most  familiar.  (3)  The  third  question  of  method  involves  the  relation 
or  correlation  of  the  metaphysical  interpretation  with  that  of  the 
natural  or  physical  science.  Two  points  are  fundamental  here.  In  the 
first  place,  it  must  be  borne  in  mind  that  it  is  the  same  world  with 
which  the  plain  man,  the  man  of  science,  and  the  metaphysician  are 
concerned.  We  cannot  partition  off  the  external  world  to  the  plain 
man,  the  atoms  and  ethers  to  the  man  of  science,  leaving  the  meta- 


THE   PRESENT   PROBLEMS   OF   METAPHYSICS      253 

physician  in  exclusive  and  solitary  possession  of  the  world  of  con- 
sciousness. It  is  the  same  world  for  all.  The  metaphysician  cannot 
shift  the  physical  world,  with  its  oceans  and  icebergs,  its  vast  plane- 
tary systems  and  milky  ways,  on  to  the  shoulders  of  the  physicist. 
This  is  the  metaphysician's  own  recalcitrant  world,  which  will  doubt- 
less task  all  his  resources  to  explain.  In  the  second  place,  though  it 
is  the  same  world  that  is  clamoring  for  interpretation,  it  is  a  world 
that  passes  through  successive  transformations,  in  order  to  adapt  itself 
to  progressive  modes  of  interpretation.  The  plain  man  is  called  to  pass 
through  a  species  of  Copernican  revolution  that  subordinates  the  phe- 
nomenon to  its  ground,  before  he  can  become  a  man  of  science.  In 
turn,  the  man  of  science  must  go  through  the  Copernican  process,  and 
learn  to  subordinate  his  atoms  and  ethers  to  consciousness  before  he 
can  become  a  metaphysician.  And  it  is  this  transformation  that  marks 
one  of  the  most  fundamental  steps  in  the  method  of  metaphysics. 
The  world  must  experience  this  transformation,  and  it  must  become 
habitual  to  the  thinker  to  subordinate  the  physical  to  the  mental 
before  the  metaphysical  point  of  view  can  be  other  than  foreign  to 
him.  If,  then,  it  be  the  same  content  with  which  the  sciences  and 
metaphysics  are  called  on  to  deal,  it  is  clear  that  we  have  on  our 
hands  another  problem  on  the  answer  to  which  the  fate  of  meta- 
physics vitally  depends;  the  question  of  the  correlation  of  its  method 
with  that  of  the  sciences  so  that  it  may  stand  vindicated  as  the  final 
interpretation  of  things. 

Ill 

QUESTION  OF  THE  CORRELATION  OF  METAPHYSICS  AVITH  THE  SCIENCES 

We  have  reached  two  conclusions  that  are  vital  here:  (1)  that  the 
meta]3hysical  way  of  looking  at  the  world  involves  a  transformation 
of  the  world  of  physical  science;  (2)  that  it  is  the  same  world  that  lies 
open  to  both  science  and  metaphysics.  Out  of  this  arises  the  pro- 
blem of  the  correlation  oi  the  two  views;  the  two  interpretations  of 
the  world.  If  science  be  right  in  conceiving  the  world  under  such 
categories  as  quantity  and  natural  causation;  if  science  be  right 
in  seeking  a  mechanical  explanation  of  phenomena  (that  is,  one  that 
excludes  prevision,  purpose,  and  aim);  and  if  metaphysics  be  right 
in  refusing  to  accept  this  explanation  as  final  and  in  insisting  that 
the  principle  of  ultimate  interpretation  is  teleological,  that  it  falls 
under  the  categories  of  prevision,  purpose,  and  aim;  then  it  is  clear 
that  the  problem  of  correlation  is  on  our  hands.  In  dealing  with  this 
problem,  it  will  be  convenient  to  separate  it  into  two  questions:  (1) 
that  of  the  fact;  (2)  that  of  its  rationale.  The  fact  of  the  correlation 
is  a  thing  of  common  experience.  We  have  but  to  consider  the  way 
in  which  this  Congress  of  Science  has  been  brought  about  in  order  to 


254  METAPHYSICS 

have  an  exhibition  of  the  method  of  correlation.  Originating  first  in 
the  sphere  of  thought  and  purpose,  the  design  has  been  actuaUzed 
through  the  operation  of  mechanical  agencies  which  it  has  some- 
how contributed  to  liberate.  On  the  scale  of  individual  experience 
we  have  the  classic  instance  of  the  arm  moving  through  space  in 
obedience  to  a  hidden  will.  There  can  be  no  question  as  to  the  fact 
and  the  great  difficulty  of  metaphysics  does  not  arise  in  the  task  of 
generalizing  the  fact  and  conceiving  the  world  as  a  system  of  thought- 
purposes  working  out  into  forms  of  the  actual  through  mechanical 
agencies.  This  generalization  somehow  lies  at  the  foundation  of  all 
metaphysical  faith,  and,  this  being  the  case,  the  real  task  here,  aside 
from  the  profounder  question  of  the  rationale,  is  that  of  exhibiting 
the  actual  points  of  correlation;  those  points  in  the  various  stages 
of  the  sciences  from  physics  to  ethics  and  religion,  at  which  the 
last  category  or  result  of  science  is  found  to  hold  as  its  immediate 
implication  some  first  term  of  the  more  ultimate  construction  of 
metaphysics.  The  working  out  of  this  task  is  of  the  utmost  import- 
ance, inasmuch  as  it  makes  clear  to  both  the  man  of  science  and  the 
metaphysician  the  intrinsic  necessity  of  the  correlation.  It  is  a  task 
analogous  to  the  Kantian  deduction  of  the  categories. 

IV 

QUESTIONS    OF   THE    ULTIMATE    NATURE    OP   EEALITT 

We  come,  then,  to  the  question  of  the  rationale  of  this  correlation, 
and  it  is  clear  here  that  we  are  dealing  with  a  phase  of  the  problem 
of  the  ultimate  nature  of  reality.  For  the  question  of  the  correlation 
now  is  how  it  is  possible  that  our  thoughts  should  affect  things  so 
that  they  move  in  response;  how  mind  influences  body  or  the  re- 
verse, how,  when  we  will,  the  arm  moves  through  space.  And  with- 
out going  into  details  of  discussion  here,  let  us  say  at  once,  that 
whatever  the  situation  may  be  for  any  science,  — and  it  maybe  that 
some  form  of  dualism  is  a  necessary  presupposition  of  science,  — 
for  metaphysics  it  is  clear  that  no  dualism  of  substances  or  orders 
can  be  regarded  as  final.  The  life  of  metaphysics  depends  on  finding 
the  one  for  the  many;  the  one  that  when  found  will  also  ground  the 
many.  If,  then,  the  phenomenon  of  mind  and  body  presents  the 
appearance  of  a  correspondence  of  two  different  and,  so  far  as  can 
be  determined,  mutually  exclusive  agencies,  the  problem  of  meta- 
physics is  the  reduction  of  these  agencies  to  one  species.  Here  we 
come  upon  the  issue  between  materialism  and  immaterialism.  But 
inasmuch  as  the  notion  of  metaphysics  itself  seems  to  exclude  ma- 
terialism, the  vital  alternative  is  that  of  immaterialism.  Again,  if 
psycho-physics  presents  as  its  basal  category  a  parallelism  between 
two  orders  of  phenomena,  psychic  and  physical,  it  is  the  business  of 


THE   PRESENT  PROBLEMS   OF   METAPHYSICS      255 

metaphysics  to  seek  the  explanation  of  this  dualism  in  some  more 
ultimate  and  unitary  conception.  Now,  since  the  very  notion  of 
metaphysics  again  excludes  the  physical  alternative  from  the  cate- 
gory of  finality,  we  are  left  with  the  psychic  term  as  the  one  that, 
by  virtue  of  the  fact  that  it  embodies  a  form  of  conscious  activ- 
ity, promises  to  be  most  fruitful  for  metaphysics.  From  one  point  • 
of  view,  then,  we  have  reduced  our  world  to  immaterialism;  from 
another,  to  some  form  or  analogue  of  the  psychic.  Now  it  is  not 
necessary  here  to  carry  the  inquiry  further  in  this  direction.  For 
what  metaphysics  is  interested  in,  specially,  is  the  fact  that  the 
world  must  be  reduced  to  one  kind  of  being  and  one  type  of  agency. 
If  this  be  done,  it  is  clear  that  the  dualism  of  body  and  mind  and 
the  parallel  orders  of  psycho-physics  cannot  be  regarded  as  final,  but 
must  take  their  places  as  phenomena  that  are  relative  and  reducible 
to  a  more  fundamental  unity.  The  metaphysician  will  say  that  the 
arm  moves  through  space  in  response  to  the  will,  and  that  every- 
where the  correlation  between  mechanical  and  teleological  agency 
takes  place  because  in  the  last  analysis  there  is  only  one  type  of  agency; 
an  agency  that  finds  its  initiative  in  interest,  thought,  purpose, 
design,  and  thus  works  out  its  results  in  the  fields  of  space  and 
mechanical  activities. 

Furthermore,  on  the  question  to  which  these  considerations  lead 
up;  that  of  the  ultimate  interpretation  we  are  to  put  on  the  reality 
of  the  world,  the  issue  is  not  so  indeterminate  as  it  might  seem  from 
some  points  of  view.  Takhig  it  that  the  very  notion  of  metaphysics 
excludes  the  material  and  the  physical  as  ultimate  types  of  the  real, 
we  are  left  with  the  notions  of  the  immaterial  and  the  psychic;  and 
while  the  former  is  indefinite,  it  is  a  fact  that  in  the  psychic  and 
especially  in  the  form  of  it  which  man  realizes  in  his  own  experience, 
he  finds  an  intelligible  type  and  the  only  one  that  is  available  to  him 
for  the  definition  of  the  immaterial.  He  has  his  choice,  then,  either 
to  regard  the  world  as  absolutely  opaque,  showing  nothing  but  its 
phenomenal  dress  which  ceases  to  have  any  meaning;  or  to  apply 
to  the  world's  inner  nature  the  intelligible  types  and  analogies  of 
his  own  form  of  being.  That  this  is  the  alternative  that  is  embodied 
in  the  existence  of  metaphysics  is  clearly  demonstrated  by  the  fact 
that  the  metaphysical  interpretation  embodies  itself  in  the  cate- 
gories of  reason,  design,  purpose,  and  aim.  Whatever  difficulties  we 
may  encounter,  then,  in  the  use  and  application  of  the  psychic  analogy 
in  determining  the  nature  of  the  real,  it  is  clear  that  its  employment 
is  inevitable  and  indispensable.  Let  us,  then,  employ  the  term  ra- 
tional to  that  characterization  of  the  nature  of  things  which  to  meta- 
ph^'sics  is  thus  inevitable  and  indispensable.  The  world  must  in  the 
last  analysis  be  rational  in  its  constitution,  and  its  agencies  and  forms 
of  being  must  be  construed  as  rational  in  their  type. 


256  METAPHYSICS 

And  here  we  come  upon  the  last  question  in  this  field,  that  of  the 
ultimate  being  of  the  world.  We  have  already  concluded  that  the 
real  is  in  the  last  analysis  rational.  But  we  have  not  answered  the 
question  whether  there  shall  be  one  rational  or  many.  Now  it  has 
become  clear  that  with  metaphysics  unity  is  a  cardinal  interest; 
that,  therefore,  the  world  must  be  one  in  thought,  purpose,  aim. 
And  it  is  on  this  insight  that  the  metaphysical  doctrine  of  the  ab- 
solutfe  rests.  There  must  be  one  being  whose  thought  and  purpose  are 
all-inclusive,  in  order  that  the  world  may  be  one  and  that  it  may 
have  meaning  as  a  whole.  But  the  world  presents  itself  as  a  plurality 
of  finite  existents  which  our  metaphysics  requires  us  to  reduce  in  the 
last  analysis  to  the  psychic  type.  What  of  this  plurality  of  psychic 
existents?  It  is  on  this  basis  that  metaphysics  constructs  its  doctrine 
of  individuality.  Allowing  for  latitude  of  opinion  here,  the  trend 
of  metaphysical  reflection  sets  strongly  toward  a  doctrine  of  realitj^ 
that  grounds  the  world  in  an  Absolute  whose  all-comprehending 
thought  and  purpose  utters  or  realizes  itself  in  the  plurality  of  finite 
individuals  that  constitutes  the  world;  the  degree  of  reality  that 
shall  be  ascribed  to  the  plurality  of  individuals  being  a  point  in 
debate,  giving  rise  to  the  contemporary  form  of  the  issue  between 
idealism  and  realism.  Allowing  for  minor  differences,  however, 
there  is  among  metaphysicians  a  fair  degree  of  assent  to  the  doctrine 
that  in  order  to  be  completely  rational  the  world  of  individual  plural- 
ity must  be  regarded  as  implying  an  Absolute,  which,  whether  it  is 
to  be  conceived  as  an  individual  or  not,  is  the  author  and  bearer  of 
the  thought  and  design  of  the  world  as  a  whole. 


QUESTIONS   OF   METAPHYSICAL   KNOWLEDGE   AND   ULTIMATE   CRITEEIA 

OF   TRUTH 

We  have  only  time  to  speak  very  briefly,  in  conclusion,  of  two 
vital  problems  in  metaphysics:  (1)  that  of  the  nature  and  limits  of 
metaphysical  knowledge;  (2)  that  of  the  ultimate  criteria  of  truth.  In 
regard  to  the  question  of  knowledge,  we  may  either  identify  thought 
with  reality,  or  we  may  regard  thought  as  wholly  inadequate  to  repre- 
sent the  real;  in  one  case  we  will  be  gnostic,  in  the  other  agnostic. 
Now  whatever  may  be  urged  in  favor  of  the  gnostic  alternative,  it 
remains  true  that  our  thought,  in  order  to  follow  along  intelligible 
lines,  must  be  guided  by  the  categories  and  analogies  of  our  own 
experience.  This  fixes  a  limit,  so  that  the  thought  of  man  is  never  in 
a  position  to  grasp  the  real  completely.  Again,  whatever  may  be 
urged  in  behalf  of  the  agnostic  alternative,  it  is  to  be  borne  in  mind 
that  our  experience  does  supply  us  with  intelligible  types  and  cate- 
gories ;  and  that  under  the  impulse  of  the  infinite  and  absolute,  or 


THE   PRESENT   PROBLEMS   OF   METAPHYSICS      257 

the  transcendent,  to  which  our  thought  responds  (to  put  it  no 
stronger),  a  dialectical  activity  arises;  on  the  one  hand,  the  appli- 
cation of  the  experience-analogies  to  determine  the  real;  on  the 
other,  the  incessant  removal  of  limits  by  the  impulse  of  transcend- 
ence (as  we  may  call  it).  Thus  arises  a  movement  of  approxima- 
tion which  while  it  never  completely  compasses  its  goal,  yet  proceeds 
along  intelligent  lines;  constitutes  the  mind's  effort  to  know;  and 
results  in  an  approximating  series  of  intelligible  and  relatively  ade- 
quate conceptions.  Metaphysically,  we  are  ever  approximating  to 
ultimate  knowledge;  though  it  can  never  be  said  that  we  have  at- 
tained it.  The  type  of  metaphysical  knowledge  cannot  be  character- 
ized, therefore,  as  either  gnostic  or  agnostic. 

As  to  the  question  of  ultimate  criteria,  it  is  clear  that  we  are  here 
touching  one  of  the  living  issues  of  our  present-day  thought.  Shall 
the  judgment  of  truth,  on  which  certitude  must  found,  exclude 
practical  considerations  of  value,  or  shall  the  consideration  of  value 
have  weight  in  the  balance  of  certitude  ?  On  this  issue  we  have  at 
the  opposite  extremes  (1)  the  pnre  rationalist  who  insists  on  the 
rigid  exclusion  from  the  epistemological  scale  of  every  consideration 
except  that  of  pure  logic.  The  truth  of  a  thing,  he  urges,  is  always 
a  purely  logical  consideration.  On  the  other  hand,  we  have  (2)  the 
pure  pragmatist,  who  insists  on  the  "vnll  to  believe"  as  a  legitimate 
datum  or  factor  in  the  determination  of  certitude.  The  pragmatic 
platform  has  two  planks:  (1)  the  ontological — we  select  our  world 
that  we  call  real  at  the  behest  of  our  interests;  (2)  the  ethical  —  in 
such  a  world  practical  interest  has  the  right  of  way  in  determining 
what  we  are  to  accept  as  true  as  well  as  what  we  are  to  choose  as 
good.  It  is  my  purpose  in  thus  outlining  the  extremes  of  doctrine 
to  close  with  a  suggestion  or  two  toward  less  ultra-conclusions.  It 
is  a  sufficient  criticism  on  the  pure  rationalist's  position  to  point  out 
the  fact  that  his  separation  of  practical  and  theoretic  interests  is  a 
pure  fiction  that  is  never  realized  anywhere.  The  motives  of  science 
and  the  motives  of  practice  are  so  blended  that  interest  in  the  con- 
clusion always  enters  as  a  factor  in  the  process.  A  conclusion  reached 
by  the  pure  rationalist's  method  would  be  one  that  would  only 
interest  the  pure  rationalist  in  so  far  as  he  could  divest  himself  of  all 
motives  except  the  bare  love  of  fact  for  its  own  sake.  The  pure 
pragmatist  is,  I  think,  still  more  vulnerable.  He  must,  to  start  with, 
be  a  pure  subjective  idealist,  otherwise  he  would  find  his  world  at 
many  points  recalcitrant  to  his  ontology.  Furthermore,  the  mere 
will  to  believe  is  arbitrary  and  involves  the  suppression  of  reason.  In 
order  that  the  will  to  believe  may  work  real  conviction,  the  point 
believed  must  at  least  amount  to  a  postulate  of  the  practical  reason; 
it  must  become  somehow  evident  that  the  refusal  to  believe  would 
create  a  situation  that  would  be  theoretically  unsound  or  irrational; 


258  METAPHYSICS 

as,  for  instance,  if  we  assume  that  the  immortality  of  the  soul  is  a 
real  postulate  of  practical  reason,  it  must  be  so  because  the  negative 
of  it  would  involve  the  irrationality  of  our  world;  and  therefore  a 
degree  of  theoretic  imperfection  or  confusion.  Personally  I  believe 
the  lines  here  converge  in  such  a  way  that  the  ideal  of  truth  will 
always  be  found  to  have  practical  value;  and  conversely,  as  to  prac- 
tical ideals,  that  a  sound  practical  postulate  will  have  weight  in  the 
theoretic  scales.  And  it  is  doubtless  true,  as  Professor  Royce  urges 
in  his  presidential  address  on  The  Eternal  and  The  Practical,  that 
all  judgments  must  find  their  final  warrant  at  the  Court  of  the 
Eternal  where,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  the  theoretical  and  practical 
coalesce  into  one. 


At  the  close  of  the  work  of  this  Section  and  upon  the  invitation  of 
Dr.  Armstrong,  a  number  of  distinguished  members  in  attendance 
joined  freely  in  the  discussion,  to  the  great  pleasure  of  the  many 
specialists  who  were  present.  Among  those  participating  were 
Professor  Boltzmann  of  Vienna,  Professor  Hoeffding  of  Copenhagen, 
Professor  Calkins  of  Wellesley,  and  Professor  French  of  the  Uni- 
versity of  Nebraska,  to  whom  replies  were  made  by  the  principal 
speakers,  Messrs.  Taylor  and  Ormond. 


SHORT  PAPERS 

A  short  paper  was  contributed  to  the  work  of  the  Section  by  Professor  W.  P. 
Montague  of  Columbia  University,  on  the  "  Physical  Reality  of  Secondary  Quali- 
ties." The  speaker  said  that  from  the  beginning  of  modern  philosophy  there  has 
existed  a  strong  tendency  among  aU  schools  of  thought  —  monists  of  the  idealistic 
or  materialistic  types,  as  well  as  outspoken  dualists  —  to  treat  the  distinction 
between  primary  and  secondary  qualities  as  coincident,  so  far  as  it  goes,  with 
the  distinction  between  physical  and  psychical.  Colors,  sounds,  odors,  etc.,  are 
regarded  as  purely  subjective  or  mental  in  their  nature,  and  as  having  no  true 
membership  in  the  physical  order;  while  correlativeiy  all  special  forms  and 
relations  have  been  in  their  turn  extruded  from  the  field  of  the  psychical.  Let  it 
be  noted  that  introspection  offers  little  or  nothing  in  support  of  this  view.  There 
is  nothing,  for  example,  about  the  color  red  that  would  make  it  appear  more  dis- 
tinctively psychical  or  subjective  than  a  figure  or  a  motion.  The  perception  of 
a  square  or  a  triangle  is  not  a  square  or  triangular  perception;  but  neither  is  the 
perception  of  red  or  blue  a  red  or  blue  perception.  Now  with  the  affective  or 
emotional  contents  of  experience  the  case  is  quite  different. 

A  feeling  of  pain  is  a  painful  feeling,  a  consciousness  of  anger  is  an  angry  con- 
sciousness. Pains  are  more  and  less  painful,  according  as  we  are  more  and  less 
aware  of  them.  With  feehngs  and  volitions  esse  is  indeed  percipi.  Colors  and 
other  secondary  qualities,  however,  do  not  seem  thus  to  increase  or  diminish 
in  their  reality  concomitantly  with  our  perceptions  of  them.  Red  is  red,  neither 
more  nor  less,  regardless  of  the  amount  to  which  we  attend  to  it.  And  yet  it 
remains  true  that,  notwithstanding  this  seeming  objectivity,  the  secondary  qual- 
ities have  long  been  contrasted  with  the  primary,  and  classed  along  with  the 
affective  and  volitional  states  as  purely  subjective  facts.  It  has  always  seemed 
curious  that  a  view  so  important  as  this  in  its  consequences,  and  so  radically  at 
variance,  not  only  with  Pre-Cartesian  philosophy,  but  also  with  our  instinctive 
beliefs,  should  have  won  its  way  to  the  position  of  an  accepted  dogma;  and  the 
purpose  of  this  paper  was  first  to  examine  the  grounds  upon  which  this  belief 
rests,  and  second  to  show  that  the  problem  of  the  independent  reality  of  the 
physical  world  and  the  problem  of  the  relation  of  physical  and  psychical  appear 
in  a  clearer  and  more  hopeful  light  when  disentangled  from  the  quite  different 
problem  of  the  relation  of  primary  and  secondary  qualities. 

There  were  two  reasons  why  the  older  or  Pre-Cartesian  view  of  this  question 
should  give  place  to  the  modern  doctrine.  First,  because  of  the  rediscovery  of 
the  idea  of  mechanism,  without  which  predictive  science  had  been  virtually  im- 
possible. The  second  reason  for  reducing  the  secondary  qualities  to  a  merely 
subjective  status  lay  in  the  fact  that  they  are  much  more  dependent  than  the 
primary  qualities  upon  the  bodily  organism  of  the  one  who  perceives  them. 
In  closing  Professor  Montague  said:  — 

"I  wish  in  closing  to  point  out  two  consequences  of  the  view  which  I  have 
been  opposing.  First,  the  present  paradoxical  status  of  the  eternal  world;  second, 
the  equally  paradoxical  status  of  the  relation  of  that  world  to  the  world  of  mind. 
Berkeley  was  the  first  thinker  clearly  to  perceive  the  unsubstantial  nature  of  a 
world  made  up  solely  of  primary  qualities.  Indeed,  in  the  last  analysis,  a  world 
of  primary  qualities,  and  nothing  else,  is  a  world  of  relations  without  terms,  a 
geometrical  fiction,  the  objective  (or,  for  that  matter,  the  subjective)  existence 


260  METAPHYSICS 

of  which  the  ideaUst  would  be  right  in  denying.  In  Biology  we  have  abandoned 
obscurantist  methods,  and  no  longer  attribute  the  distinctive  vital  functions  of 
growth  and  reproduction  to  a  vital  force  or  vital  substance,  but  solely  to  the 
peculiar  configuration  of  the  material  elements  of  a  ceU.  Why  may  we  not  in 
psychology  with  equal  propriety  attribute  the  distinctively  psychical  functions 
of  subjectivity  or  consciousness,  not  to  the  action  of  a  hj^per-psychical  soul-sub- 
stance, nor  to  the  presence  of  a  transcendental  ego,  but  simply  to  that  peculiar 
configuration  of.  sensorv  elements  which  constitutes  a  what  we  call  psychosis?  " 


SECTION  B  — PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION 


SECTION   B 
PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION 


{Hall  1,  September  21,  3  p.  m.) 


Chairman:     Professor  Thomas  C.  Hall,  Union  Theological  Seminary,  N.  Y. 
Speakers:     Professor  Otto  Pfleiderer,  University  of  Berlin. 

Professor  Ernst  Troeltsch,  University  of  Heidelberg. 
Secretary:  Dr.  W.  P.  Montague,  Columbia  University. 


THE  RELATION  OF  THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION  TO 
THE   OTHER   SCIENCES 

BY    PROFESSOR    OTTO    PFLEIDERER 

[D.  Otto  Pfleiderer,  Professor  of  Theology,  University  of  Berlin  since  1875. 
b.  September  1,  1839,  Stetten,  Wiirtemberg.  Grad.  Tiibingen,  1857-61. 
Post-grad.  ibid.  1864-68.  City  Professor,  Heilbronn,  1868-69;  Superin- 
tendent, Jena,  1869-70;  Professor  of  Theology,  Jena,  1870-75.  Author  of 
Religion  and  its  Essential  Characteristics;  Religious  Philosophy  upon  His- 
torical Foundation;   and  many  other  works  and  papers  on  Theology.] 

In  order  to  answer  this  question,  we  need  to  consider  a  prelimi- 
nary question,  namely,  whether  religion  can  be  regarded  as  the 
object  of  scientific  knowledge  in  the  same  manner  as  other  processes 
of  the  intellectual  life  of  the  race,  such  as  law,  history,  and  art.  It 
is  well  known  that  this  question  has  not  always  received  an  affirm- 
ative answer,  and  indeed  it  can  never  be  answered  in  the  affirmative 
so  long  as  the  position  is  maintained  that  the  only  religion  is  that  of 
the  Christian  Church,  whose  doctrines  and  teachings  rest  upon  an 
immediate  divine  revelation,  and  that  these  must  be  accepted  by 
men  in  blind  belief.  Under  the  position  of  an  authoritative  ecclesias- 
tical faith  there  can  indeed  exist  a  theoretical  consideration  of  the 
doctrines  of  faith,  as  it  was  the  case  with  the  scholastic  theology 
of  the  Middle  Ages,  which  with  great  earnestness  sought  to  harmon- 
ize faith  and  knowledge;  nevertheless,  no  one  of  the  present  day 
would  give  to  the  scholastic  theology  the  name  of  science  with  the 
modern  meaning  of  the  term  science.  The  scholastic  theology  used 
great  formal  acuteness  and  skill  in  the  work  of  defining  and  defend- 
ing ecclesiastical  traditions,  still  there  was  lacking  that  which  for 
us  is  the  essential  condition  of  scientific  knowledge,  the  free  examin- 
ation of  tradition  according  to  the  laws  of  human  thought  and  the 


264  PHILOSOPHY  OF   RELIGION 

analogy  of  the  general  experience  of  humanity.  The  great  hindrance 
to  the  progress  of  the  knowledge  of  religion  was  the  accepted  posi- 
tion that  the  truth  of  the  ecclesiastical  doctrines  was  beyond  human 
reason  and  outside  of  human  examination,  since  their  truth  rested 
upon  an  immediate  divine  revelation.  Whether  this  supernatural 
authority  was  ascribed  to  the  Church  or  the  Bible  makes  very  little 
difference,  for  in  either  case  the  assumption  of  such  an  authority 
is  a  hindrance  to  the  free  examination  of  that  which  claims  to  be  the 
divine  revealed  truth. 

But  is  this  assumption  really  justifiable  in  the  nature  of  the  case? 
Do  the  doctrines  of  the  Church  rest  upon  a  supernatural  divine 
revelation?  So  soon  as  this  question  was  really  earnestly  considered, 
and  the  thinking  mind  could  not  always  avoid  the  consideration, 
then  there  was  revealed  the  'inadequacy  of  the  assumption.  Two 
ways  of  examination  led  to  a  common  critical  result,  the  philosophical 
analysis  of  the  religious  consciousness  and  the  historical  comparison 
of  various  religions.  The  first  to  enter  upon  these  ways  and  at  the 
same  time  to  become  the  founder  of  the  modern  science  of  religion 
was  the  keen  Scotch  thinker  David  Hume.  Truly  the  thought  of 
Hume  was  still  a  one-sided,  disorganizing  skepticism;  even  as  his 
theory  of  knowledge  disturbed  the  truth  of  all  our  previous  common- 
sense  opinions  and  conceptions,  so  also  his  philosophy  of  religion 
sought  to  demonstrate  that  all  religion  cannot  be  proved  and  is  full 
of  doubt,  and  that  the  origin  of  religion  was  neither  to  be  found  in 
divine  revelation  nor  in  the  reason  of  man,  but  in  the  passions  of 
the  heart  and  in  the  illusions  of  imagination.  As  unsatisfactory  as 
this  result  was,  nevertheless  it  gave  an  important ,  advance  to  the 
rational  study  of  religion  in  two  directions,  in  that  of  religion  being 
an  experience  of  the  inner  life  of  the  soul  and  in  that  of  religion 
being  a  fact  of  human  history. 

Kant  added  the  positive  criticism  of  reason  to  the  negative  skep- 
ticism of  Hume;  that  is,  Kant  showed  that  the  human  intellect 
moved  independently  in  the  formation  of  theoretical  and  practical 
judgments,  and  that  the  various  materials  of  thought,  desire,  and 
feelings  were  regulated  by  the  intellect  according  to  innate  original 
ideas  of  the  true  and  good  and  beautiful.  Thus  as  a  natural  result 
there  came  the  conception  that  the  doctrines  of  belief  arose  not  as 
complete  truths,  given  by  divine  revelation,  but,  like  every  other 
form  of  conscious  knowledge,  these  came  to  us  through  the  activity 
of  our  own  mind,  and  that  therefore  these  doctrines  cannot  be  re- 
garded as  of  absolute  authority  for  all  time,  but  that  we  are  to  seek 
to  understand  their  origin  in  historical  and  psychical  motives.  So 
far  as  one  looked  at  the  ceremonial  forms  of  positive  religion,  these 
motives  indeed  were  found  according  to  Kant  in  irrational  concep- 
tions, but  as  far  as  the  essence  of  religion  was  concerned  they  were 


RELIGION  AND  THE  OTHER  SCIENCES  265 

rather  found  to  be  rooted  in  the  moral  nature  of  man.  This  is  the 
consciousness  of  obhgation  of  the  practical  reason  or  of  the  con- 
science, which  raises  man  to  a  faith  in  the  moral  government  of  the 
world,  in  immortality  and  God.  With  the  reduction  of  religion 
from  all  external  forms,  doctrines,  and  ceremonies  and  the  finding 
of  the  real  essence  of  religion  in  the  human  mind  and  spirit,  the  way 
was  opened  to  a  knowledge  of  religion  free  from  all  external  authority. 
Those  philosophers  who  came  after  Kant  followed  essentially  this 
course,  though  here  and  there  they  may  separate  in  their  opinions 
according  to  their  thought  of  the  psychological  function  of  religion. 
When  Kant  had  emphasized  the  close  connection  between  religion 
and  the  moral  obligation,  then  came  Schleiermacher,  who  empha- 
sized the  feeling  of  our  dependence  upon  the  Eternal,  and  who  sought 
to  find  the  explanation  of  all  religious  thoughts  and  conceptions 
in  the  many  relations  of  the  feeling  to  religious  experience.  Hegel 
on  the  other  hand  sought  the  truth  of  religion  in  the  thought  of  the 
absolute  spirit  as  found  in  the  finite  spirit.  Thus  Hegel  made  reli-. 
gion  a  sort  of  popular  philosophy. 

At  present  all  agree  that  all  sides  of  the  soul-life  have  part  in 
religion;  now  one  side  may  be  the  more  prominent,  now  another, 
according  to  the  peculiarity  of  certain  religions  or  the  individual 
temperaments.  The  philosophy  of  religion  has,  in  common  with 
scientific  psychology,  the  question  of  the  relation  of  feeling  to  the 
intellect  and  the  will,  and  as  yet  there  may  be  many  views  of  this 
question.  Altogether  the  philosophy  of  religion  is  looking  for  im- 
portant solutions  to  many  of  its  problems  from  the  realm  of  the 
present  scientific  psychology.  Experiences,  such  as  religious  con- 
versions, appear  under  this  point  of  view  as  ethical  changes  in  which 
the  aim  of  a  personal  life  is  changed  from  a  carnal  and  selfish  end  to 
that  of  a  spiritual  and  altruistic  purpose.  These  are  extraordinary 
and  seemingly  supernatural  processes;  nevertheless  in  them  there 
can  still  be  found  a  certain  development  of  the  soul-life  according 
to  law.  Modern  psychology  especially  has  thrown  light  upon  the 
abnormal  conditions  of  consciousness  which  have  so  often  been  made 
manifest  in  the  religious  experience  of  all  times.  That  which  religious 
history  records  concerning  inspiration,  visions,  ecstasy,  and  revelation, 
we  now  classify  with  the  well-known  appearances  of  hypnotism, 
the  induction  of  conceptions  and  motives  of  the  will  through  foreign 
suggestion  or  through  self-suggestion,  of  the  division  of  conscious- 
ness in  different  egos,  and  in  the  union  of  several  consciousnesses 
into  one  common  mediumistic  fusion  of  thought  and  will.  The  explan- 
ation of  these  experiences  may  not  yet  be  satisfactory,  but  never- 
theless we  do  not  doubt  the  possibility  of  a  future  explanation  from 
the  general  laws  controlling  the  life  of  the  soul.  The  fact  that  we  can 
through  psychological  experiments  produce  such  abnormal  conditions 


266  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION 

of  consciousness  justifies  us  in  taking  the  position,  that  certain 
psychical  laws  are  at  the  foundation  of  these  conditions  which  in 
their  kind  are  as  natural  and  regular  in  their  functions  as  the  physical 
laws  which  we  observe  in  physical  experiments.  These  solutions 
which  modem  psychology  so  far  has  given,  and  hopes  stiU  further 
to  give,  are  of  great  importance  to  the  philosophy  of  reHgion.  They 
are  an  indorsement  of  the  general  principle  which  one  hundred  years 
ago  had  been  advanced  by  critical  speculation,  namely,  that  in  all 
experiences  of  the  religious  life  the  same  principles  which  control 
the  human  mind  in  all  other  intellectual  and  emotional  fields  shall 
hold  sway.  Nothing  therefore  should  hinder  us  in  scientific  research 
from  following  the  well-defined  Tnaxims  of  thought,  and  unreservedly 
applying  the  same  methods  of  scientific  analysis  in  theology  as  is 
done  generally  in  the  other  sciences. 

The  claim  of  the  Church  to  infallibility  and  divine  inspiration  of 
its  dogmas  is  weakened  under  this  view  of  the  work  of  the  philosophy 
of  reHgion.  Prophetical  inspiration  and  ecstasy,  which  usually  were 
thought  to  be  supernatural  revelations,  are  now  declared  by  the 
present  psychology  to  come  under  the  category  of  other  analogous 
experiences,  such  as  the  action  of  mental  powers  which,  under  definite 
conditions  of  individual  gifts  and  on  historical  occasions,  have 
manifested  themselves  in  extraordinary  forms  of  consciousness. 
However,  these  enthusiastic  forms  of  prophetical  consciousness 
cannot  be  accepted  for  a  higher  form  of  knowledge  or  even  as  of 
divine  origin  and  as  an  infallible  proclamation  of  the  truth;  on  the 
contrary,  these  forms  are  to  be  judged  as  pathological  appearances, 
which  may  be  more  harmful  than  beneficent  for  the  ethical  value 
of  the  prophetical  intuition.  At  least,  it  has  come  to  pass  that  aU 
forms  of  revelation  must  come  under  the  examination  of  a  psycho- 
logical analysis  and  of  an  analogical  judgment.  Hence  their  tradi- 
tional nimbus  of  imique.  supernatural,  and  absolute  authority  is  for 
all  time  destroyed. 

We  are  carried  to  the  same  r^ult  by  the  comparative  study  of  the 
history  of  rehgions.  The  study  shows  us  that  the  Christian  Church, 
with  its  dogma  of  the  divine  inspiration  of  the  Bible,  does  not  stand 
alone;  that  before  and  after  Christianity  other  rehgions  made 
exaetiy  the  same  claims  for  their  sacred  scriptures.  By  the  pious 
Brahman  the  Veda  is  regarded  as  infallible  and  eternal;  he  beUeves 
the  hymns  of  the  old  seers  were  not  composed  by  the  seers  them- 
selves, but  were  taken  from  an  original  copy  in  heaven.  The  Buddhist 
sees  in  the  sayings  of  his  sacred  book  '■' Dhammapadam '"  the  exact 
inheritance  of  the  infaUible  words  of  his  omniscient  teacher  Buddha. 
For  the  confessor  of  Ahuramazda  the  Zenda vesta  contains  the 
scriptiiral  revelation  of  the  good  spirit  unto  the  prophet  Zarathustra; 
accordins  to  the  rabbis  the  laws  revealed  unto  Mos^  on  Mount  Sinai 


RELIGION   AND   THE   OTHER   SCIENCES  267 

were  even  before  the  creation  of  the  world  the  object  of  the  observ^a- 
tion  of  God;  for  the  faithful  Mohammedan  the  Koran  is  the  copy 
of  an  ever-present  original  in  heaven,  the  contents  of  which  were 
dictated  word  for  word  to  Mohammed  by  the  angel  Gabriel.  Whoever 
ponders  the  similar  claims  of  all  these  rehgions  for  the  infallibility  of 
their  sacred  books,  to  him  it  becomes  difficult  to  hold  the  dogma 
of  the  Christian  Church  concerning  the  inspiration  and  infaUibihty  of 
the  Bible  as  alone  true  and  the  similar  dogmas  of  other  rehgions 
as  being  false.  Rather  he  will  accept  the  xievr  that  in  all  these  ex- 
amples there  are  found  the  same  motives  of  the  rehgions  mind,  'that 
here  is  given  an  expression  to  the  same  need  common  to  aU  seeking 
for  an  absolute  and  abiding  basis  for  their  faith. 

The  study  of  the  comparison  of  rehgions  has  discovered  in  religions 
other  than  that  of  Christianity  many  very  striking  parallels  to  many 
narratives  and  teachings  of  the  Bible.  It  may  be  weU  to  recall  very 
briefly  some  of  the  important  points.  Owing  to  the  fact  that  the 
Assyrian  cuneiform  writings  have  now  been  deciphered,  there  has 
been  found  a  stor}'  of  the  creation  which  has  many  characteristics 
in  common  with  those  of  the  Bible.  There  is  found  a  story  of  a  flood, 
which  in  its  very  details  can  be  regarded  as  the  forerunner  of  the 
story  of  the  flood  in  the  Bible.  There  have  been  found  Assyrian 
penitential  psalms,  which,  in  consciousness  of  gmlt  and  in  earnest- 
ness of  prayer  for  forgiveness,  can  well  be  compared  with  many 
psalms  of  the  Bible.  Recentl}'  the  Code  of  the  AssjTian  King  Ham- 
murabi, who  reigned  two  thousand  three  hundred  years  before 
Christ,  has  been  discovered.  The  similarity  of  this  Code  with  many 
of  the  early  Mosaic  Laws  has  called  general  attention  to  this  fact.  In 
the  Persian  rehgion  there  are  found  teachings  of  the  Kingdom  of  God, 
of  the  good  spirits  who  surround  the  throne  of  God,  of  the  Spirit 
hostile  to  God  and  of  an  army  of  his  demons,  of  the  judgment  of  each 
soul  after  death,  of  a  heaven  with  eternal  hght  and  of  the  dark 
abyss  of  hell,  of  the  future  struggle  of  the  multitudes  of  good  and  bad 
spirits  and  the  ^•ictory  over  the  bad  through  a  divine  hero  and 
saviour,  of  the  general  resurrection  of  the  dead,  of  the  awful  destruc- 
tion of  the  world  and  the  creation  of  a  new  and  better  world,  — 
teachings  which  are  also  found  in  the  later  Jewish  theology  and  apo- 
calypse, so  that  the  acceptance  of  a  dependence  of  Jewish  upon 
corresponding  Persian  teaching  can  hardly  be  avoided.  Also  Grecian 
influence  is  obser^'ed  in  later  Jewish  hterature,  in  proverbs,  in  the 
wisdom  of  Solomon  and  the  Son  of  Sirach;  especially  in  the  Alex- 
andrian Jewish  theology  are  found  Platonic  thoughts  of  an  eternal, 
ideal  world,  of  the  heavenly  home  of  the  soul,  and  the  Stoic  concep- 
tion of  a  world-ruling  di\ine  Logos. 

It  is  from  this  source  that  the  Logos  to  which  Philo  had  already 
ascribed  the  meaning  of  the  Son  of  God  and  the  Bringer  of  a  di^-ine 


268  PHILOSOPHY  OF   RELIGION 

revelation  crossed  over  into  Christian  theology  and  became  the 
foundation  of  the  dogma  of  the  Church  concerning  the  person  of 
Christ.  Of  still  greater  importance  than  even  all  this  was  the  opening 
of  the  Indian  and  especially  the  Buddhistic  religious  writings.  In 
these  we  have,  five  hundred  years  before  Christianity,  the  revelation 
of  redemptive  religion,  resting  upon  the  ethical  foundation  of  the 
abnegation  of  self  and  the  withdrawal  from  the  world.  In  the  centre 
of  this  religion  is  Gautama  Buddha,  the  ideal  teacher  of  redeeming 
truth,  whose  human  life  was  adorned  by  the  faith  of  his  followers 
with  a  crown  of  wonderful  legends;  from  an  abode  in  heaven,  out  of 
mercy  to  the  world,  he  descended  into  the  world,  conceived  and 
born  of  a  virgin  mother,  greeted  and  entertained  by  heavenly  spirits, 
recognized  beforehand  by  a  pious  seer  as  the  future  redeemer  of  the 
world;  as  a  youth  he  manifested  a  wisdom  beyond  that  of  his  teachers. 
Then  after  the  reception  of  an  illuminating  revelation,  he  victoriously 
overcomes  the  temptation  of  the  devil,  who  would  cause  him  to  be- 
come faithless  to  his  call  to  redemption.  Then  he  begins  to  preach 
of  the  coming  of  the  Kingdom  of  Justice,  and  sends  forth  his  dis- 
ciples, two  by  two,  as  messengers  of  his  gospel  to  all  people.  Although 
he  declares  that  it  is  not  his  calling  to  perform  miracles,  neverthe- 
less the  legends  indeed  tell  how  many  sick  were  healed,  how  with  the 
contents  of  a  small  basket  hundreds  were  fed,  how  possessed  of  all 
knowledge  he  reveals  hidden  things;  how  overcoming  the  limitations 
of  space  and  time,  swaying  in  the  air,  being  transfigured  in  a  heavenly 
light,  he  reveals  himself  to  his  disciples  just  before  his  death.  And 
at  last,  in  the  faith  of  his  followers,  having  passed  from  the  position 
of  a  human  teacher  to  that  of  an  eternal  heavenly  spirit  and  lord 
of  the  world,  he  is  exalted  as  the  object  of  prayer  and  reverence,  to 
many  millions  of  the  human  race  in  Southern  and  Eastern  Asia. 

It  is  hardly  possible  that  the  knowledge  of  this  parallel  from  India 
to  the  New  Testament,  and  of  the  Babylonian  and  Persian  parallel 
to  the  Old  Testament,  can  be  without  influence  upon  the  religious 
thought  of  Christian  people.  Although  we  may  be  ever  so  much 
convinced  concerning  the  essential  superiority  of  our  religion  over 
all  other  religions,  nevertheless  the  dogmatic  contrast  between  abso- 
lute truth  on  the  one  side  and  complete  falsity  on  the  other  can  no 
more  be  maintained.  In  place  of  this  view  there  must  enter  the  view 
of  a  relative  grade  of  differences  between  the  higher  and  lower  stages 
of  development.  No  longer  can  we  see  in  other  religions  only  mis- 
takes and  fiction,  but  under  the  husk  of  their  legends  many  precious 
kernels  of  truth  must  be  seen,  expressions  of  inner  religious  feelings 
and  of  noble  ethical  sentiments.  One  should  therefore  accept  the 
position  not  to  object  to  the  same  discrimination  between  husk  and 
kernel  in  the  matter  of  one's  own  religion,  and  to  recognize  in  its 
inherited  traditions  and  dogmas  legendary  elements,  the  explanation 


RELIGION  AND  THE  OTHER  SCIENCES  269 

of  which  is  to  be  found  in  psychical  motives  and  in  historical  sur- 
roundings, even  as  they  are  found  in  the  corresponding  parts  of 
religions  other  than  the  Christian  religion.  Therefore  the  historical 
comparison  of  religions  takes  us  away  from  an  absolute  dogmatic 
positivism  to  a  relative  evolutionary  manner  of  study,  placing  all 
religions  without  exception  under  the  laws  of  time  progression  and 
under  the  causal  connection  of  the  law  of  cause  and  effect.  The 
isolation  of  religion  therefore  is  no  more.  It  is  regarded  as  being 
a  part  of  other  human  historical  affairs,  and  must  yield  to  the  test  of  a 
thorough  unhindered  research.  The  value  of  the  Christian  religion 
can  never  suffer  in  the  view  of  a  reasonable  man,  when  it  is  not  ac- 
cepted in  blind  faith,  but  as  the  result  of  discriminating  comparison. 
As  the  evolutionary  philosophy  of  religion  uses  the  method  of 
science  without  exception  in  the  case  of  all  historical  religions,  so 
also  it  does  not  shrink  from  taking  up  the  question  of  the  beginning 
of  religion,  but  believes  that  here  also  is  found  the  key  in  the  ana- 
lytical, critical,  and  comparative  method.  And  here  is  found  the 
assistance  of  the  comparative  study  of  languages,  ethnology,  and 
paleontology. 

The  celebrated  Sanscrit  scholar.  Max  Miiller,  sought  in  the  com- 
parative study  of  mythology  to  prove  the  etymological  relation  of 
many  of  the  Grecian  gods  and  heroes  with  those  of  the  mythology 
of  India  and  to  trace  the  common  origin  of  all  these  mythical  beings 
and  legends  in  the  personification  of  the  movements  of  the  heavenly 
bodies,  the  thunder  and  lightning,  the  tempest  and  the  rain.  All 
mythical  belief  in  gods  of  the  Indo-Germanic  peoples  seems  to  have 
arisen  out  of  a  poetical  view  and  dramatic  personification  of  the 
powers  of  nature.  Suggestive  as  this  hypothesis  is,  it  is  not  by  any 
means  sufficient  to  give  us  a  complete  explanation  of  the  subject. 
In  fact,  others  have  shown  that  primitive  religion  does  not  altogether 
consist  in  mythical  conceptions,  but  mainly  in  reverential  actions, 
sacrifices,  sacraments,  vows,  and  other  similar  cults,  which  have 
very  little  to  do  with  the  atmospherical  powers  of  nature,  but  rather 
with  the  social  life  of  primitive  people.  And  when  once  the  sight 
was  clearly  directed  to  the  social  meaning  of  the  religious  rites,  it  was 
then  observed  that  even  the  earliest  legends  concerning  the  gods 
were  connected  far  more  closely  with  the  habits  and  customs  of 
early  society  than  with  the  facts  of  nature.  Tylor's  celebrated  book 
concerning  "Primitive  Civilization"  is  written  from  this  standpoint, 
an  epoch-making  book,  showing  the  original  close  connection  of 
religion  with  the  entire  civilization  of  humanity,  with  the  views  of 
life  and  death,  the  social  customs,  the  forms  of  law,  their  strivings  in 
art  and  science;  a  book  with  a  large  amount  of  information,  brought 
together  from  observation  on  all  sides.  In  this  channel  are  found  all 
the  researches  which  to-day  are  classified  under  the  name  of  Folk- 


270  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION 

lore;  seeking  to  gather  the  still  existing  characteristic  customs  and 
forms,  legends,  stories,  and  sayings,  in  order  to  compose  these  and  to 
discover  the  survivals  of  earliest  religion,  poetry,  and  civilization  of 
humanity.  The  gain  of  this  study  pursued  with  so  great  diligence  is 
not  to  be  underrated.  These  studies  show  that  all  that,  which  at  one 
time  existed  as  faith  in  the  spirit  of  humanity,  possessed  within  its 
very  nature  the  strongest  power  of  continuance,  so  that  in  new  and 
strange  conditions  and  in  other  forms  it  continued  to  remain.  Under 
all  changes  and  progress  of  history  there  is  still  found  an  unbroken 
connection  of  constant  development. 

As  important,  however,  as  the  possession  of  a  general  knowledge 
of  historical  forms  of  development  is  to  the  philosophy  of  religion, 
nevertheless  the  possession  of  this  knowledge  is  not  wholly  a  fulfill- 
ment of  the  purpose  of  the  philosophy  of  religion.    To  understand  a 
development  means  not  merely  to  know  how  one  thing  follows  as  the 
result  of  the  other,  but  also  to  understand  the  law  which  lies  at  the 
foundation  of  all  empirical  changes  and  at  the  same  time  controls 
the  end  of  the  development.     If  this  principle  holds  good  in  the 
understanding  of  the  development  in  the  processes  of  nature,  much 
more  does  the  principle  hold  good  in  understanding  the  processes  of 
intellectual  development  of  humanity,  which  have  for  us  not  only 
a  theoretical,  but  at  the  same  time  an  eminently  practical  interest. 
The  philosopher  of  religion  sees  in  religious  history  not  merely  the 
coming  together  of  similar  forms,  but  an  advance  from  the  lowest 
stage  of  childlike  ignorance  to  an  ever  purer  and  richer  realization 
of  the  idea  of  religion,  a  divinely  ordained  progress  for  the  education 
of  humanity  from  the  slavery  of  nature  to  the  freedom  of  the  spirit. 
The  question  now  arises :  where  do  we  find  the  principle  and  law  of 
this  ever-rising  development?     Where  do  we  find  the  measure  of 
judgment  for  the  relative  value  of  religious  appearances?   It  is  clear 
that  the  general  principle  of  the  complete  development  cannot  be 
found  in  a  single  fact  which  is  only  one  of  the  many  manifestations 
of  the  general  principle,  and  it  is  just  as  clear  that  the  absolute 
norm  of  judgment  is  not  found  in  a  single  fact  always  relative, 
presenting  to  us  the  object  of  judgment  and  therefore  being  impos- 
sible to  stand  as  the  norm  of  judgment.    Therefore  the  principle  of 
religious  development  and  the  norm  of  its  judgment  can  only  be 
found  in  the  inner  being  of  the  spirit  of  humanity,  namely,  in  the 
necessary  striving  of  the  mind  into  an  harmonious  arrangement  of 
all  our  conceptions,  or  the  idea  of  the  truth,  and  into  the  complete 
order  of  all  our  purposes,  or  the  idea  of  the  good.    These  ideas  unite 
in  the  highest  unity,  in  the  Idea  of  God.   Therefore  the  consciousness 
of  God  is  the  revelation  of  the  original  innate  longing  of  reason  after 
complete  unity  as  a  principle  of  universal  harmony  and  consistence  in 
all  our  thinking  and  willing.   Hence,  in  the  first  place,  arises  the  result 


RELIGION  AND   THE  OTHER  SCIENCES  271 

that  the  development  of  the  consciousness  of  God  in  the  history  of 
religion  is  always  dependent  upon  the  existing  conditions  of  the  two 
united  sides,  the  theoretical  perception  of  the  truth  and  the  moral 
standard  of  life.  In  the  second  place  the  result  arises  that  the  judg- 
ment of  the  value  of  all  appearances  in  the  history  of  religion  depends 
as  to  whether  and  how  far  these  appearances  agree  with  the  idea  of 
the  true  and  the  good,  and  correspond  with  the  demands  of  reason 
and  conscience.  That  science  which  is  engaged  with  the  idea  of  the 
good  we  name  Ethics;  that  which  is  engaged  with  the  last  principles 
of  the  perception  of  truth,  using  the  expression  of  Aristotle,  we 
may  name  Metaphysics,  or  following  Plato  —  Dialectic.  Recognizing 
then  in  the  idea  of  God  the  synthesis  of  the  idea  of  the  true  and  the 
good,  the  philosophy  of  religion  is  closely  related  with  both.  Ethics 
and  Metaphysics. 

At  present  the  relation  of  religion  to  morality  is  an  object  of  much 
controversy.  There  are  many  who  hold  that  morality  without  religion 
is  not  only  possible  but  also  very  desirable;  since  they  are  of  the 
opinion  that  moral  strength  is  weakened,  the  will  is  without  freedom, 
and  its  motives  corrupted  on  account  of  religious  conceptions.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  Church,  considering  the  experience  of  history, 
finds  that  religion  has  ever  proved  itself  to  be  the  strongest  and  most 
necessary  aid  to  morality.  In  this  contest  the  philosophy  of  rehgion 
occupies  the  position  of  a  judge  who  is  called  upon  to  adjust  the  rela- 
tive rights  of  the  parties.  The  philosophy  of  religion  brings  to  light 
the  historical  fact  that  from  the  very  beginnings  of  human  civilization, 
social  life  and  morality  were  closely  connected  with  religious  con- 
ceptions and  usages,  and  indeed  always  so  interchangeable  in  their 
influence  that  the  position  of  social  civilization  on  the  one  side  cor- 
responded with  the  position  of  religious  civilization  on  the  other, 
just  as  the  water-level  in  two  communicating  pipes.  Therefore  it 
follows  that  it  is  unjust  and  not  historical  to  blame  religion  on  ac- 
count of  the  defects  of  a  national  and  temporal  morality;  for  these 
defects  of  morality,  with  the  corresponding  errors  of  religion,  find  a 
common  ground  in  a  low  stage  of  development  of  the  entire  civiliza- 
tion of  the  people  of  the  time  and  age.  Further,  it  becomes  the  task 
of  the  philosophy  of  religion  to  examine  whether  this  correspondence 
of  religion  and  morality,  recognized  in  history,  is  also  found  in  the 
very  nature  of  morality  and  religion.  This  question  in  the  main  is 
answered  without  doubt  in  the  affirmative,  for  it  is  clear  that  the 
religious  feeling  of  dependence  upon  one  all-ruling  power  is  well 
adapted  not  only  to  make  keen  the  moral  consciousness  of  obligation 
and  to  deepen  the  feeling  of  responsibility,  but  also  to  endow  moral 
courage  with  power  and  to  strengthen  the  hope  of  the  solution  of 
moral  purposes.  The  clearer  religious  faith  comprehends  the  rela- 
tion of  man  to  God,  so  much  the  more  will  that  faith  prove  itself  as 


272  PHILOSOPHY   OF  RELIGION 

a  strong  motive  and  a  great  incentive  of  the  moral  life.  Such  a  con- 
ception will  not  make  the  moral  will  unfree  but  truly  free,  not  in  the 
sense  of  a  selfish  choice,  but  in  the  sense  of  a  love  that  serves,  knowing 
itself  as  an  instrument  of  the  divine  will,  who  binds  us  all  into  a 
social  organism,  the  kingdom  of  God.  And,  on  the  other  hand,  the 
more  ideal  the  moral  view  of  life,  the  higher  and  greater  its  aims, 
the  more  it  recognizes  its  great  task  to  care  for  the  welfare  not  only 
of  the  individual  but  of  all,  to  cooperate  in  the  welfare  and  develop- 
ment of  all  forms  of  society,  the  more  earnestly  the  moral  mind  will 
need  a  sincere  faith  that  this  is  God's  world,  that  above  all  the 
changes  of  time  an  eternal  will  is  on  the  throne,  whose  all-wise  guid- 
ance causes  everything  to  be  for  the  best  unto  those  who  love  him. 
A  like  middle  position  of  arbitration  falls  to  the  philosophy  of 
religion  in  the  matter  of  the  relation  of  religion  to  science.  The 
first  demand  of  science  is  freedom  of  thought,  according  to  its  own 
logical  laws,  and  its  fundamental  assumption  is  the  possibility  of 
the  knowledge  of  the  world  on  the  basis  of  the  unchangeable  laws 
of  all  existence  and  events.  With  this  fundamental  demand  science 
places  itself  in  opposition  to  the  formal  character  of  ecclesiastical 
doctrine  so  far  as  the  doctrine  claims  infallible  authority  resting 
upon  a  divine  revelation.  And  the  fundamental  assumption  of  the 
regular  law  of  the  course  of  the  world  is  in  opposition  to  the  contents 
of  ecclesiastical  doctrine  concerning  the  miraculous  interposition 
in  the  course  of  nature  and  of  history.  To  the  superficial  observer 
there  appears  therefore  to  exist  an  irreconcilable  conflict  between 
science  and  religion.  Here  is  the  work  of  the  philosophy  of  religion, 
to  take  away  the  appearance  of  an  irreconcilable  opposition  between 
science  and  religion,  in  that  the  philosophy  of  religion  teaches  first 
of  all  to  distinguish  between  the  essence  of  religion  and  the  ecclesias- 
tical doctrines  of  a  certain  religion,  and  to  comprehend  the  historical 
origin  of  these  doctrines  in  the  forms  of  thought  of  past  times.  To 
this  purpose  the  method  of  psychological  analysis  and  of  historical 
comparison  mentioned  above  is  of  service.  When,  then,  by  this 
critical  process  religion  is  traced  to  its  real  essence  in  the  emotional 
consciousness  of  God,  to  which  the  dogmatic  doctrines  stand  as 
secondary  products  and  varied  symbols,  then  it  remains  to  show 
that  between  the  essence  of  religion  and  that  which  science  demands 
and  presupposes,  there  exists  not  conflict  but  harmony.  When  the 
idea  of  God  is  recognized  as  the  synthesis  of  the  ideas  of  the  true 
and  the  good,  so  then  must  all  truth  as  sought  by  science,  even  as  the 
highest  good,  which  the  system  of  ethics  places  as  the  purpose  of  all 
action  —  these  must  be  recognized  as  the  revelation  of  God  in  his 
eternal  reason  and  goodness.  The  laws  of  our  rational  thinking 
then  cannot  be  in  conflict  with  divine  revelation  in  history,  and  the 
laws  of  the  natural  order  of  the  world  can  no  more  stand  in  conflict 


RELIGION   AND    THE    OTHER   SCIENCES  273 

with  the  world-governing  Omnipotence;  but  both,  the  laws  of  our 
thinking  and  those  of  the  real  world,  reveal  themselves  as  the  har- 
monious revelations  of  the  creative  reason  of  God,  which,  according 
to  Plato's  fitting  word,  is  the  efficient  ground  of  being  as  well  as  of 
knowing.  It  is  therefore  not  merely  a  demand  of  religious  belief  that 
there  is  real  truth  in  our  God-consciousness,  that  there  should  be 
an  activity  and  revelation  of  God  himself  in  the  human  mind;  it  is 
also  in  the  same  manner  a  demand  of  science  considering  its  last 
principles,  that  the  world,  in  order  to  be  known  by  us  as  a  rational, 
regulated  order,  must  have  for  its  principle  an  eternal  creative 
reason.  Long  ago  the  old  master  of  thinking,  Aristotle,  recognized 
this  fact  clearly,  when  he  said  that  order  in  the  world  without  a  prin- 
ciple of  order  could  be  as  little  thinkable  as  the  order  of  an  army 
without  a  commanding  general. 

But  while  it  is  true  that  science,  as  the  ground  of  the  possibility 
of  its  knowledge  of  the  truth,  must  presuppose  the  same  general 
principle  of  intellectual  knowledge  which  religion  has  as  the  object 
of  its  practical  belief,  then  by  principle  the  apprehension  is  excluded 
that  any  possible  progress  on  the  part  of  science  in  its  knowledge 
of  the  world  can  ever  destroy  religion.  We  are  rather  the  more 
justified  in  the  hope  that  all  true  knowledge  of  science  will  be' a  help 
to  religion,  and  will  serve  as  the  means  of  purifying  religion  from  the 
dross  of  superstition. 

Truly  it  can  easily  be  shown  that  a  divine  government  of  the 
world  breaking  through,  and  now  and  then  suspending  the  regular 
order  of  nature  through  miraculous  intervention,  would  not  be  more 
majestic,  but  far  more  limited  and  human,  than  such  a  government 
which  reveals  itself  as  everywhere  and  always  the  same  in  and 
through  its  own  ordained  laws  in  the  world.  And  again,  that  a 
revelation  prescribing  secret  and  incomprehensible  doctrines  and 
rites,  demanding  from  humanity  a  blind  faith,  would  far  less  be  in 
harmony  with  the  guiding  wisdom  and  love  of  God,  and  far  less 
could  work  for  the  intellectual  liberty  and  perfection  of  humanity, 
than  such  a  revelation  which  is  working  in  and  through  the  reason 
and  conscience  of  humanity,  and  is  realizing  its  purpose  in  the  pro- 
gressive development  of  our  intellectual  and  moral  capacities  and 
powers.  When  therefore  science  raises  critical  misgivings  against 
the  supernatural  and  irrational  doctrines  of  positive  religion,  then 
the  real  and  rightly  understood  interests  of  religion  are  not  harmed 
but  rather  advanced;  for  this  criticism  serves  religion  in  helping 
it  to  become  free  from  the  unintellectual  inheritance  of  its  early 
days,  in  helping  religion  to  consider  its  true  intellectual  and  moral 
essence,  and  to  bring  to  a  full  display  all  the  blessed  powers  which 
are  concealed  within  its  nature,  to  press  through  the  narrow  walls  of 
an  ecclesiasticism  out  into  the  full  life  of  humanity,  and  to  work  as 


274  PHILOSOPHY  OF   RELIGION 

leaven  for  the  ennoblement  of  humanity.  Not  in  conflict  with  science 
and  moral  culture,  but  only  in  harmony  with  these,  can  religion  come 
nearer  to  the  attainment  of  its  ideal,  which  consists  in  the  worship  of 
God  in  spirit  and  in  truth.  Even  though  they  may  not  be  conscious 
of  their  purpose,  but  nevertheless  in  fact  all  honest  work  of  science 
and  all  the  endeavors  of  social  and  ethical  humanity  have  part  in 
the  attainment  of  this  ideal. 

It  is  the  work  of  the  philosophy  of  religion  to  make  clear  that  all 
work  of  the  thinking  and  striving  spirit  of  humanity,  in  its  deepest 
meaning,  is  a  work  in  the  kingdom  of  God,  as  service  to  God,  who  is 
truth  and  goodness.  It  is  the  work  of  the  philosophy  of  religion 
to  explain  various  misunderstandings,  to  bring  together  opposing 
sides,  and  so  to  prepare  the  way  for  a  more  harmonious  cooperation 
of  all,  and  for  an  always  hopeful  progress  of  all  on  the  road  to  the 
high  aims  of  a  humanity  fraternally  united  in  the  divine  spirit. 


MAIN   PROBLEMS   OF  THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF   RELIGION: 
PSYCHOLOGY    AND    THEORY    OF    KNOWLEDGE    IN 
THE  SCIENCE  OF   RELIGION 

BY  PROFESSOR  ERNST  TROELTSCH 

{Translated  from  the  German  by  Dr.  J.  H.  Woods,  Harvard  University.) 

[Ernst  Troeltscli,  Professor  of  Systematic  Theology,  University  of  Heidelberg, 
since  1894.  b.  February  17,  1865,  Augsburg,  Bavaria.  Doctor  of  Theology. 
Professor  University  of  Bonn,  1892-94.  Author  of  John  Gerhard  and  Mel- 
anchthon;  Richard  Rubbe;  The  Scientific  Attitude  and  its  Demands  on 
Theology;  The  Absoluteness  of  Christianity,  and  of  the  History  of  Religion; 
Political  Ethics  and  Christianity;  The  Historic  Element  in  Kant's  Religious 
Philosophy  .^ 

The  philosophy  of  religion  of  to-day  is  philosophy  of  religion  so  far 
only,  and  in  such  a  sense,  as  this  word  means  science  of  religion  or 
philosophy  with  reference  to  religion.  The  science  of  religion  of 
former  days  was  first  dogmatic  theology,  deriving  its  dogmas  from 
the  Bible  and  from  Church  tradition,  expounding  them  apologetic- 
ally with  the  metaphysical  speculation  of  the  later  period  of  anti- 
quity, and  regarding  the  non-Christian  religions  as  sinful  derange- 
ments and  obscure  fragments  of  the  primitive  revelation.  This 
lasted  sixteen  centuries,  and  is  confined  to-day  to  strictly  ecclesias- 
tical circles.  Next,  science  of  religion  became  natural  theology, 
which  proved  the  existence  of  God  by  the  nature  of  thought  and  by 
the  constitution  of  reality,  and  also  the  immortality  of  the  soul  by 
the  concept  of  the  soul  and  by  moral  demands,  thus  constructing 
natural  or  rational  dogmas  and  putting  these  dogmas  into  more 
or  less  friendly  relations  with  traditional  Christianity.  This  lasted 
about  two  centuries,  and  is  to-day  of  the  not  strictly  ecclesiastical 
or  pietistic  circles,  which  still  wish  to  hold  fast  to  religion.  Both 
kinds  of  science  of  religion  exist  no  longer  for  the  strict  science. 
The  first  was,  in  reality,  supernaturalistic  dogmatics,  the  second 
was,  in  reality,  a  substitution  of  philosophy  for  religion.  The  first 
was  demolished  by  the  criticism  of  miracles  in  the  eighteenth  century, 
the  second  by  the  criticism  of  knowledge  in  the  nineteenth  century, 
which,  in  its  turn,  rests  upon  Hume  and  Kant. 

The  science  of  religion  of  to-day  keeps  in  touch  with  that  which 
without  doubt  factually  exists  and  is  an  object  of  actual  experience, 
the  subjective  religious'  consciousness.  The  distrust  of  ecclesiastical 
and  rationalistic  dogmas  has  made,  in  the  thought  of  the  present, 
every  other  treatment  impossible.  So  the  spirit  of  empiricism  has 
here  as  at  other  points  completely  prevailed.  But  empiricism  in  this 
field  means  psychological  analysis.    This  analysis  is  pursued  by  the 


276  PHILOSOPHY   OF   RELIGION 

present  to  the  widest  extent :  on  the  one  side  by  anthropologists  and 
archaeologists,  who  investigate  the  life  of  the  soul  in  primitive  peoples 
and  thus  indicate  the  particular  function  and  condition  of  religion 
in  these  states;  on  the  other  side,  by  the  modern  experimental 
psychologists  and  psychological  empiricists,  who,  by  self-observa- 
tion, and  especially  by  the  collection  of  observations  by  others  and  of 
personal  testimony,  study  religion,  and  then,  from  the  point  of  view 
of  the  concepts  of  experimental  psychology,  examine  the  main 
phenomena  thus  found. 

Now,  such  an  empirical  psychology  of  religion  has  been  constructed 
with  considerable  success.  In  this  German  literature,  it  is  true,  has 
cooperated  to  a  slight  degree  only.  The  German  theologians  have 
held  to  the  older  statements  of  the  psychology  of  Kant,  of  Schleier- 
macher,  of  Hegel,  and  of  Fries,  alone,  which,  in  principle,  were  on 
the  right  path,  but  which  combined  the  purely  psychological  with 
metaphysical  and  epistemological  problems  to  such  a  degree  that  it 
was  impossible  to  reach  a  really  unprejudiced  attitude.  German 
psychologists  remain,  furthermore,  under  the  spell  of  psycho-physio- 
logy and  of  quantitative  statements  of  measure,  and  have,  conse- 
quently, not  liked  to  advance  into  this  field,  which  is  inaccessible 
to  such  statements.  More  productive  than  the  German  psychology 
for  this  subject  is  the  French,  which  has  attacked  the  complex  facts 
far  more  courageously.  Here,  however,  under  the  predominance  of 
positivism,  there  prevails,  on  the  whole,  the  tendency  to  regard 
religion,  in  its  essence,  anthropologically  or  medically  and  patho- 
logically in  connection  with  bodily  conditions.  This  is  the  confusion 
of  conditions  and  origins  with  the  essence  of  the  thing  itself,  which 
can  be  determined  only  by  the  thing,  and  is,  by  no  means,  bound 
exclusively  to  these  conditions.  Notwithstanding,  the  works  of 
Marillier,  Murisier,  and  Flournoy  have  considerably  aided  the 
problem.  More  impartially  than  all  of  these,  the  English  and  Ameri- 
can psychology  has  investigated  our  subject.  Here  we  have  a  master- 
piece in  the  Gifford  Lectures  of  William  James,  which  collects  into 
a  single  reservoir  similar  investigations  such  as  have  been  carried  on 
by  Coe  and  Starbuck.  There  is  here  no  tendency  to  a  mechanism  of 
consciousness,  or  to  the  dogma  of  the  causal  and  necessary  structure 
of  consciousness.  And  to  just  this  is  due  the  freshness  and  impartial- 
ity of  the  analyses  which  James  gives  out  of  his  enviable  knowledge  of 
characteristic  cases.  James  rightly  emphasizes  the  endlessly  different 
intensity  of  religious  experiences,  and  the  great  number  of  points 
of  view  and  of  judgments  which  thereby  results.  He  also  rightly 
emphasizes  the  connection  of  this  different  intensity  with  irreducible 
typical  constitutions  of  the  soul's  life,  with  the  optimistic  and  the 
melancholy  disposition;  hence  there  arise  constantly,  even  within 
the  same  religion,  essentially  different  types  of  religiousness.    Limit- 


PSYCHOLOGY   IN  THE  SCIENCE  OF   RELIGION    277 

ing  himself,  then,  to  the  most  intense  experiences,  he  decides  that 
the  characteristic  of  religious  states  is  the  sense  of  presence  of  the 
divine,  which  one  might  perhaps  describe  in  other  terms,  but  which 
still  continues  the  specifically  divine,  with  the  opposed  emotional 
effects  of  a  solemn  sense  of  contrast  and  of  enthusiastic  exaltation. 
He  pictures  these  senses  of  presence,  and  illustrates  them  by  vision- 
ary and  hallucinatory  representations  of  the  abstract.  With  this  are 
connected  impulsive  and  inhibitive  conditions  for  the  appearance  of 
these  senses  of  presence  and  of  reality,  descriptions  of  the  effects 
upon  the  emotional  life  and  action,  and,  above  all,  the  analysis  of 
the  event  usually  called  conversion,  in  which  the  religious  experi- 
ence out  of  subconscious  antecedents  becomes,  in  various  ways,  the 
centre  of  the  soul's  life.  All  this  is  description,  but  it  is  based  upon 
a  mass  of  examples  and  explained  by  general  psychological  cate- 
gories which,  by  the  occurrence  of  the  religious  event  only,  receive 
a  thoroughly  specific  coloring.  It  is  a  description  after  the  manner 
of  Kirchhoff's  mechanics;  permanent  and  similar  types,  and,  like- 
wise, similar  conditions  for  their  relations  to  the  rest  of  the  soul's 
life  are  sought  out  everywhere,  without  maintaining  to  have  proven 
at  the  same  time,  in  this  way,  an  intellectual  necessity  for  the  con- 
nection. But  the  characteristic  peculiarity  of  religious  phenomena 
is  thus  conceived  as  in -no  other  previous  analysis. 

All  this  is  still,  however,  nothing  more  than  psychologic.  For  the 
science  of  religion  it  accomplishes  nothing  more  than  the  psycho- 
logical determination  of  the  peculiarity  of  the  phenomenon,  of  its 
environment,  its  relations  and  consequences.  It  is  evident  that  the 
phenomenon  occurs  in  an  indefinite  number  of  varieties;  and  the 
chosen  point  of  departure,  in  unusual  and  excessive  cases,  frequently 
diffuses  over  religion  itself  the  character  of  the  bizarre  and  abnor- 
mal. Consequently  nothing  whatever  is  said  about  the  amount  of 
truth  or  of  reality  in  these  cases.  This,  by  the  very  principles  of 
such  a  psychology,  is  iihpossible.  It  analyzes,  produces  types  and 
categories,  points  out  comparatively  constant  connections  and  inter- 
actions. But  this  cannot  be  the  last  word  for  the  science  of  religion. 
It  demands,  above  all,  empirical  knowledge  of  the  phenomenon;  but 
it  demands  this  only  in  order,  on  the  basis  of  this  knowledge,  to  be 
able  to  answer  the  question  of  the  amount  of  truth.  But  this  leads 
to  an  entirely  different  problem,  that  of  the  theory  of  knowledge, 
which  has  its  own  conditions  of  solution.  It  is  impossible  to  stop 
at  a  merely  empirical  psychology.  The  question  is  not  merely  of 
given  facts,  but  of  the  amount  of  knowledge  in  these  facts.  But  pure 
empiricism  will  not  succeed  in  answering  this  question.  The  question 
with  regard  to  the  amount  of  truth  is  always  a  question  of  validity. 
The  question  with  regard  to  validity  can,  however,  be  decided  only 
by  logical  and  by  general,  conceptual  investigations.    Thus  we  pass 


278  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION 

over  from  the  ground  of  empiricism  to  that  of  rationahsm,  and  the 
question  is,  what  the  theory  of  knowledge  or  rationahsm  signifies 
for  the  science  of  reUgion. 

Such  a  synthesis  of  the  rational  and  irrational,  of  the  psychological 
and  the  theory  of  knowledge,  is  the  main  problem  raised  by  the 
teaching  of  Kant,  and  the  significance  of  Kant  is  that  he  clearly  and 
once  for  all  raised  the  problem  in  this  way.  He  had  the  same  strong 
mind  for  the  empirical  and  actual  as  for  the  rational  and  conceptual 
elements  of  human  knowledge,  and  constructed  science  as  a  balance 
between  the  two.  (He  destroyed  forever  the  a  priori  speculative 
rationalism  of  the  necessary  ideas  of  thought,  and  the  analytical 
deductions  from  them,  which  undertakes  to  call  reality  out  of  the 
necessity  of  thought  as  such.  He  restricted  regressive  rationalism 
to  metaphysical  hypotheses  and  probabilities,  the  evidence  for  which 
rests  upon  the  inevitability  of  the  logical  operations  which  leads  to 
them,  which,  however,  apply  general  concepts  without  reference  to 
experience,  and  therefore  become  empty,  and  thus  afford  no  real 
knowledge.)  On  the  other  hand,  he  proclaimed  the  formal,  imman- 
ent rationalism  of  experience,  in  attempting  to  unite  Hume's 
truth  with  the  truth  of  Leibnitz  and  of  Plato.  In  this  way  he  suc- 
ceeded in  grasping  the  great  problem  of  thought  by  the  root,  and 
in  putting  attempts  at  solutions  on  the  right  basis.  So  it  is  not  a 
mere  national  custom  of  German  philosophizing,  if  we  take  our 
bearings,  for  the  most  part,  from  this  greatest  of  German  thinkers, 
but  it  is,  absolutely,  the  most  fruitful  and  keenest  way  of  putting  the 
problem.  It  is  true,  the  solutions  which  Kant  made,  and  which  are 
closely  connected  with  the  classical  mechanics  of  that  time,  with 
the  undeveloped  condition  of  the  psychology  of  that  time,  and  with 
the  incompleteness  of  historical  thinking  then  just  beginning,  have 
been,  meantime,  more  than  once  given  up  again.  A  simple  return  to 
him  is  therefore  impossible.  But  the  problem  was  put  by  him  in 
a  fundamental  way,  and  his  solutions  need  nothing  more  than  modi- 
fication and  complstion. 

Now  all  this  is  especially  true  in  the  case  of  the  science  of  religion. 
Here  also  Kant  took  the  same  course,  which  seemed  to  me  right  for 
the  theoretical  knowledge  of  the  natural  sciences  and  for  anthro- 
pology. In  practical  philosophy  also,  to  which  he  rightly  counts 
philosophy  of  religion,  he  seeks  laws  of  the  practical  reason  analogous 
to  the  laws  of  theoretical  reason,  axioms  of  the  ethical,  sesthetic, 
and  religious  consciousness  which  are  already  contained  a  priori 
in  the  elementary  appearances  in  these  fields,  and,  in  application 
to  concrete  reality,  produce  just  these  activities  of  the  reason.  Here 
also  one  should  grasp  reason  only  as  contained  in  life  itself,  the 
a  priori  law  itself  already  effective  in  the  diversity  of  the  appearances 
should  make  one's  self  clear-sighted  and  so  competent  for  a  criticism 


PSYCHOLOGY   IN  THE  SCIENCE  OF   RELIGION    279 

of  the  stream  of  the  soul's  appearances.  Seizing  upon  itself  in  the 
practical  reality,  the  practical  reason  criticises  the  psychological 
complex,  rejects  as  illusion  and  error  that  which  cannot  be  com- 
prehended in  an  a  'priori  law,  selects  that  part  of  the  same  which 
needs  basis  and  centre  and  requires  only  clearness  with  regard  to 
itself,  clears  the  way  for  revelations  of  a  life  consciousness  of  its  own 
legality  and  becomes  capable  of  the  development  of  critically  purified 
experience. 

If  this  is,  in  principle,  valid,  the  Kantian  thought,  in  the  further 
detail,  is  maintained  in  principle  only  and  as  a  whole.  The  elabora- 
tion itself  will  have  to  be  quite  different  from  that  of  his  own.  Even 
by  Kant  himself,  on  this  very  point,  the  synthesis  of  empiricism  and 
rationalism  is  far  from  being  elaborated  with  the  necessarj'^  rigor  and 
consistency.  And  to-day  we  have  a  quite  differently  developed 
psychology  of  religion,  in  contrast  with  which  that  presupposed  by 
Kant  is  bare  and  thin.  Finally,  there  remain  in  the  whole  method  of 
the  critical  system  unsolved  problems;  by  failure  to  solve  these,  or 
by  too  hasty  solution,  science  of  religion,  especially,  is  affected. 

To  make  clear  the  present  condition  of  the  problem,  one  ought, 
above  all,  to  indicate  the  modifications  to  which  the  Kantian  theory 
of  religion  must  submit,  —  must  submit,  especially,  by  reason  of  a 
more  delicate  psychology,  such  as  we  have,  with  remarkable  rich- 
ness, in  James  and  the  American  psychologists  connected  with  him. 
There  are  jour  points  with  regard  to  this  question. 

The  first  is  the  question  of  the  relation  of  psychology  and  theory 
of  knowledge  in  the  very  establishment  of  the  laws  of  the  theory  of 
knowledge.  Are  not  the  search  for  and  discovery  of  the  laws  of  the 
theory  of  knowledge  themselves  possible  only  by  way  of  psychological 
ascertainment  of  facts,  itself  then  a  psychological  undertaking  and 
consequently  dependent  upon  all  its  conditions?  It  is  the  much  dis- 
cussed question  of  the  circle  which  itself  lies  at  the  outset  of  the 
critical  system.  The  answer  to  this  is  that  this  circle  lies  in  the  very 
being  of  all  knowledge,  and  must  therefore  be  resolutely  committed. 
It  signifies  nothing  more  than  the  presupposition  of  all  thought,  the 
trust  in  a  reason  which  establishes  itself  only  by  making  use  of 
itself.  The  unmistakable  elements  of  the  logical  assert  themselves 
as  logical  in  distinction  from  the  psychological,  and  from  this  point 
on  reason  must  be  trusted  in  all  its  confusions  and  entanglements  to 
recognize  itself  within  the  psychological.  It  is  the  courage  of  thought, 
as  Hegel  says,  which  may  presuppose  that  the  self-knowledge  of  rea- 
son may  trust  itself,  presuppose  that  reason  is  contained  within  the 
psychological;  or  it  is  the  ethical  and  teleological  presupposition  of 
all  thought,  as  Lotze  saj^s,  which  believes  in  knowledge  and  the 
validity  of  its  laws  for  the  sake  of  a  connected  meaning  for  reality, 
and  which,  therefore,  trusts  to  recognize  itself  out  of  the  psycholog- 


280  PHILOSOPHY   OF   RELIGION 

ical  mass.  The  establishment,  therefore,  of  the  laws  of  the  theory 
of  knowledge  is  not  itself  a  psychological  analysis,  but  a  knowledge 
of  self  by  the  logical  by  virtue  of  which  it  extricates  itself  out  of  the 
psychological  mass.  Theory  of  knowledge,  like  every  rationalism, 
includes,  it  is  true,  very  real  presuppositions  with  regard  to  the  sig- 
nificant, rational,  and  teleologically  connective  character  of  reality, 
and  without  this  presupposition  it  is  untenable;  in  it  lies  its  root. 
It  is  insight  of  former  daj'S,  the  importance  of  which,  however,  must 
constantly  be  emphasized  anew,  that  discusses  the  vaUdity  of  the 
rational  as  opposed  to  the  merely  empirical.  But  still  more  im- 
portant than  this  thesis  are  several  inferences  which  are  given 
with  it. 

The  establishment  of  the  laws  of  consciousness,  in  which  we 
produce  experience,  is  a  selection  of  the  laws  out  of  experience  itself, 
a  knowledge  of  itself  by  the  reason  contained  in  the  very  experience 
by  way  of  the  analysis  which  extracts  it.  It  is  then  an  endless  task, 
completed  by  constantly  renewed  attacks,  and  always  only  approxi- 
mately solvable.  The  complete  separation  of  the  merel}''  psychological 
and  actual  and  of  the  logical  and  necessary  will  never  be  completely 
accomplished,  but  wall  always  be  open  to  doubt;  one  can  only 
attempt  always  to  limit  more  vigorously  the  field  of  what  is  doubtful. 
And  with  this  something  further  is  connected. 

The  inexhaustible  production  of  life  becomes  constantly,  in  the 
latent  amount  of  reason,  richer  than  the  analysis  discerns,  or,  in 
other  words,  the  laws  which  are  brought  into  the  light  of  logic  will 
always  be  less  the  amount  of  reason  not  brought  into  consciousness, 
and  conscious  logic  will  always  be  obliged  to  correct  itself  and  enrich 
itself  out  of  the  unartificial  logical  operations  arising  in  contact  with 
the  object.  So  a  finished  system  of  a  priori  principles,  but  this  sys- 
tem will  always  be  in  growth,  wdll  be  obliged  unceasingly  to  correct 
itself,  and  to  contain  open  spaces. 

Finally,  and  above  all,  in  case  of  this  separation,  there  remains 
within  the  psychologically  conditioned  appearance,  a  residuum, 
which  is  either  not  conceived,  but  is  later  reduced  to  law  and  thereby 
a  conceived  phenomenon,  or  which  never  can  be  so,  and  is  therefore 
illusion  and  error.  If  the  psychological  and  the  theoretical  for  know- 
ledge are  to  be  separated,  then  that  can  occur,  not  merely  to  show 
that  both  must  always  be  together,  and  form  real  experience  only 
when  together,  but  there  must  also  be  a  rejection  of  that  which  is 
merely  psychological  and  not  rational  since  it  is  illusion  and  error. 
The  distinction  between  the  apparent  and  the  real  was  the  point 
of  departure  which  made  the  whole  theory  necessary,  and,  accord- 
ingly, the  merely  psychological  must  remain  appearance  and  error 
side  by  side  with  that  which  is  psychological  and,  at  the  same  time, 
theoretical  for  knowledge.    There  always  remains  in  consciousness 


PSYCHOLOGY  IX   THE   SCIKSXE   OF   RELIGION    281 

a  residuum  of  the  inconceivable,  that  is.  inconceivable  since  it  is 
illusion  and  error.  This  amounts  to  saying  that  reality  is  never 
fully  rational,  but  is  engaged  in  a  struggle  between  the  rational 
and  anti-rationaL  The  anti-rational  or  irrational,  in  the  sense  of 
psychological  illusion  and  error,  belongs  also  to  the  real,  and  strives 
against  the  rational.  The  true  and  rational  reality  to  be  attained 
by  thought  is  always  in  conjunction  vrith  the  untrue  reahty.  the 
psychological,  that  containing  illusion  and  error. 

All  this  signifies  that  the  rationalism  of  the  theory  of  knowledge 
must  be  conditional,  partly  owing  to  the  corrective  and  enriching 
fecundation  by  primitive  and  naive  thought,  partly  owing  to  never 
quite  separable  admixture  of  illusion  and  error.  So.  long  ago.  the 
system  of  categorical  forms,  as  Kant  constructed  it  for  theoretical 
and  practical  reason,  began  to  change,  and  can  never  again  acquire 
the  rigidity  which  Kant's  rationalism  intended  to  give  it  forever- 
more.  And  thus  the  critical  system's  rational  reality  of  law  produc-ed 
bv  reason  always  contains  below  itself  and  beside  itself  the  merely 
psychological  reahty  of  the  factual,  to  which  also  illusion  and  error 
belong.  —  a  reahty  which  can  never  be  rationalized,  but  only  set 
aside.  This .  too .  is  also  true  for  me  philosophy  of  rehgion :  the  rational 
reduction  of  the  psychological  facts  of  rehgion  to  the  general  laws  of 
consciousness  which  prevail  among  them  is  a  task  constantly  to  be 
resumed  anew  by  the  study  of  reahty.  and  foUo^va  the  movements 
of  primitive  rehgion  in  order  to  find  there  first  the  rational  bass: 
the  reduction  is.  however,  always  approximate,  can  comprehend 
the  main  points  only,  and  must  leave  much  open,  the  rational  ground 
for  which  is  not  or  not  yet  evident:  finally  it  has  unceasingly  to 
reckon  with  the  irrational  as  illusion  and  error,  which  auaches  to  the 
rational,  and  yet  is  not  explainable  by  it.  Hie  two  reahties.  which 
the  critical  system  must  recognize  at  its  very  foundation,  continue 
in  strife  with  each  other,  and  this  strife  as  the  strife  of  divine  truth 
with  human  illusion  is  for  the  science  of  religion  of  still  r!>?re  im- 
portance. 

The  second  correction  of  the  Kantian  reaching  is  only  a  further 
consequence  from  this  state  of  things.  K  the  attitude  of  psychology 
and  theory-  of  knowledge  requires  a  strict  separation,  it  requires  it 
only  for  the  purpose  of  more  correct  relation.  The  la^vs  of  the  theory 
of  knowledge  are  separated  from  the  merely  psychological  actuahty, 
but  still  can  be  produced  only  out  of  it.  Thus,  sis  a  matter  of  fact, 
psychological  analysis  is  always  the  jwresupposition  for  the  correct 
conception  of  all  these  laws.  Psychology  is  the  entrance  gate  to 
theory  of  knowledge.  This  is  true  for  theoretical  logic  as  well  as  for 
the  practical  logic  of  the  moral,  the  aesthetical.  and  the  religious. 
But  just  at  this  point  the  present,  on  the  basis  of  its  psychological 
investigation,  presses  far  beyond  the  original  form.  o£  the  Kantian 


282  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION 

teaching.    This  is  not  the  place  to  describe  this,  more  closely,  with 
reference  to  the  first  of  the  subjects  just  mentioned.    But  it  is  im- 
portant to  insist  that  this  is  especially  true  with  respect  to  the 
Kantian  doctrine  of  religion.     The  Kantian  doctrine  of  religion  is 
founded  on  the  moral  and  religious  psychology  of  Deism,  which  had 
made  the  connection,  frequent  in  experience,  of  moral  feelings  with 
religious  emotion  the  sole  basis  of  the  philosophy  of  religion,  and 
had,  in  the  manner  of  the  psychology  of  the  eighteenth  century, 
immediately  changed  this  connection  into  intellectual  reflections, 
in  accord  with  which  the  moral  law  demands  its  originator  and 
guarantee.    Kant  accepted  this  psychology  of  religion  without  proof 
and  built  upon  it  his  main  law  of  the  religious  consciousness,  in 
accordance  with  which  a  synthetic  judgment  a  priori  is  operative 
in  religion   (arising    in    the  moral  experience  of  freedom),  which 
requires  that  the  world  be  regarded  as  subject  to  the  purposes  of 
freedom.     It  is,  however,  extremely  one-sided,  to  give  religion  its 
place  just  between  the  elements,  and  a  rather  violent  translation  of 
the  religious  constitution  into  reflection.    The  error  of  this  psycho- 
logy of  religion  had  been  discovered  and  corrected  already  by  Schleier- 
macher.     But  Schleiermacher,  for  his  part  too,  also  failed  to  deny 
himself  an  altogether  too  sudden  metaphysical  interpretation  of  the 
religious  a  priori  which  he  had  demonstrated,  since  he  not  only 
described  the  a  priori  judgment  of  things,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
absolute  dependence  upon  God,  as  a  vague  feeling,  but  raised  this 
feeling,  by  reason  of  the  supposed  lack  of  difference,  in  it,  between 
thought  and  will,  reason  and  being,  to  a  world-principle,  and  inter- 
preted the  idea  of  God  contained  in  this  feeling  in  the  terms  of  his 
Spinozism,  the  lack  of  difference  between  God  and  Nature  within 
the  Absolute.     A  real  theory  of  knowledge  of  religion  must  keep 
itself  much  more  independent  of  all  metaphysical  presuppositions 
and  inferences,  and  must  admit  that  the  essence  of  the  religious 
a  priori  is   extorted   from   a   thoroughly   impartial   psychological 
analysis.    And  this  is  always  the  place  where  works,  such  as  those 
of  James,  come  into  play.    Religion  as  a  special  category  or  form  of 
psychical  constitution,  the  result  of  a  more  or  less  vague  presence 
of  the  divine  in  the  soul,  the  feeling  of  presence  and  reality  with 
reference  to  the  superhuman  or  infinite,  that  is  without  any  doubt 
a  much  more  correct  point  of  departure  for  the  analysis  of  the  rational 
a  priori  of  religion,  and  it  remains  to  make  this  new  psychology 
fruitful  for  the  theory  of  knowledge  of  religion.    That  will  be  one  of 
the  chief  tasks  of  the  future. 

The  third  change  relates  to  the  distinction  of  the  empirical  and 
intelligible  Ego,  which  Kant  connected  closely,  almost  indissolubly 
with  his  main  epistemological  thought  of  the  formal  rationalisms 
immanent  in  experience.     Kant  rationalized  the  whole  outer  and 


PSYCHOLOGY  IN  THE  SCIENCE  OF  RELIGION     283 

inner  experience,  by  means  of  a  'priori  laws,  into  a  totality,  conform- 
ing to  law,  appearing  in  intuitive  forms  of  space  and  time,  causally 
and  necessarily  rigidly  connected.  The  freedom  autonomously 
determining  itself  out  of  the  logical  idea,  and  contrasting  itself  with 
the  psychological  stream,  produces  out  of  the  confused  psycholican 
reality  this  scientific  formation  of  the  true  reality.  The  product  of 
thought,  however,  swallows  its  own  maker.  For  the  same  acts  of 
freedom,  which  autonomously  produced  the  formation  of  the  reality 
of  law,  remain  themselves  in  the  temporal  sequence  of  psychical 
events,  and,  therefore,  themselves,  with  that  formation,  lapse  into 
the  sequence  which  is  under  mechanical  law.  The  intelligible  Ego 
creates  the  world  of  law,  and  finds  itself  therein,  with  its  activity,  as 
empirical  Ego,  that  is,  as  product  of  the  great  world-mechanism  and 
of  its  causal  sequence.  It  is  an  intolerable,  violent  contradiction, 
and  it  is  no  solution  of  this  contradiction  to  refer  the  empirical  Ego 
to  appearance,  and  the  intelligible  Ego  to  actuality  existing  in  itself, 
if  the  operations  of  the  intelligible  Ego,  also  a  constituent  part  of 
what  takes  place  in  the  soul,  occur  in  time  and  so  relapse  irrecover- 
ably into  phenomenality  and  its  mechanism.  All  the  ingenuity 
of  modern  interpretation  of  Kant  has  not  succeeded  in  making  this 
circle  more  tolerable,  all  shifting  of  one  and  the  same  thing  to  differ- 
ent points  of  view  has  only  enriched  scientific  terminology  with 
masterpieces  of  parenthetical  caution,  but  not  removed  the  objection 
that  two  different  points  of  view  do  not,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  exist 
side  by  side,  but  conflict  within  the  same  object. 

This  circle  is  especially  intolerable  for  the  psychology  of  religion 
and  its  application  to  the  theory  of  knowledge.  The  psychology  of 
religion  certainly  shows  us  that  the  deeper  feeling  of  all  religion  is 
not  a  product  of  the  mechanical  sequence,  but  an  effect  of  the  super- 
sensuous  itself  as  it  is  felt  there;  it  believes  that  it  arises  in  the 
intelligible  Ego  by  way  of  some  kind  of  connection  with  the  super- 
sensuous  world.  This,  however,  becomes  completely  impossible  for 
the  Kantian  theory  of  the  empirical  Ego,  and  all  distinctions  of  a 
double  point  of  view  in  no  wise  change  the  fact  that  these  points  of 
view  are  mutually  absolutely  exclusive.  Here  we  have  the  results 
of  psychology  which  the  expression  of  religious  emotion  confirms,  in 
that  religion  can  be  causally  reduced  to  nothing  else,  totally  opposed 
to  the  consequences  of  such  a  theory  of  knowledge.  Kant  had  him- 
self often  enough  practicall}^  felt  this,  and  spoke  then  of  freedom  as 
an  experience  of  communion  with  the  supersensuous  as  a  possible 
but  unprovable  affair,  while  all  that,  in  case  of  a  strict  adherence 
to  the  phenomenality  of  time  and  of  the  theory  of  the  empirical 
Ego,  which  is  a  consequence  of  it,  is  completely  impossible.  No- 
thing can  be  of  any  assistance  here  except  a  decisive  renunciation 
of  those  epistemological  positions  which  contradict  the  results  of 


284  PHILOSOPHY   OF   RELIGION 

psychology,  and  which  are  themselves  only  doctrinaire  consequences 
from  other  positions.  Nothing  else  is  possible  but  the  modification 
of  the  phenomenality  of  time,  in  such  a  way  that  by  no  means 
everj^thing  which  belongs  to  time  belongs  also  as  a  matter  of 
course  to  phenomenality,  but  that  the  autonomous  rational  acts 
which  occur  in  the  time  series  of  consciousness  possess  their  own 
intelligible  time-form.  At  the  same  time  the  concept  of  causality 
closely  connected  with  the  concept  of  time  is  to  be  modified  so 
that  there  should  be  not  only  an  immanent  and  phenomenal  causal 
connection,  but  also  a  regular  interaction  between  phenomenal  and 
intelligible,  psychological  and  rational,  conscious  reality.  At  the 
same  time  the  conclusion  is  also  given  up,  that  the  Ego  submits 
unconditionally  and  directly  to  phenomenality  and  to  causal  neces- 
sity, while  the  same  Ego,  once  more,  in  the  same  way,  as  a  whole, 
from  another  point  of  view,  is  subordinate  to  freedom  and  auto- 
nomy, that  is,  self-constitutive  through  ideas.  The  two  Egos  must 
lie  not  side  by  side,  but  in  and  over  one  another.  It  must  be 
possible  that,  within  the  phenomenal  Ego  by  a  creative  act  of 
the  intelligible  Ego  in  it,  the  personality  should  be  formed  and 
developed  as  a  realization  of  the  autonomous  reason,  so  that  the 
intelligible  issues  from  the  phenomenal,  the  rational  from  the  psy- 
chological, the  former  elaborates  and  shapes  the  latter,  and  between 
both  a  relation  of  regular  interaction,  but  not  of  causal  constraint, 
takes  place.  This  rather  deep,  incisive  modification  is,  in  its  turn,  an 
approach  of  the  Kantian  teaching  to  empiricism,  but  still  at  the 
same  time,  in  the  destruction  and  subordination  of  the  phenomenal 
and  intelligible  world,  in  the  emphasis  upon  the  single  personality 
issuing  from  the  act  of  reason,  an  adherence  to  rationalism.  But 
since  the  distinction  and  the  interrelation  between  the  rational  and 
the  empirical  forms  the  point  of  departure  for  the  critical  system, 
and  this  point  of  departure  requires  at  the  same  time  the  moulding 
and  shaping  of  the  empirical  by  the  rational  and  the  rejection  of  the 
psychological  appearance;  a  mere  parallelism  is  altogether  impossi- 
ble, but  an  interrelation , is  included,  and  a  task  set  for  the  effort. and 
labor  which  constantly  makes  the  rational  penetrate  the  empirical. 
At  the  very  outset  we  have  the  exclusion  of  the  parallelism  and  the 
assertion  of  the  interrelation.  The  interrelation,  by  its  very  nature, 
asserts  the  interruption  of  the  causal  necessity  and  the  penetration 
of  autonomous  reason  in  this  sequence,  without  being  itself  produced 
by  this  sequence,  although  it  can  be  stimulated  and  helped  or  inhib- 
ited and  weakened  by  it.  Thus,  in  such  a  case  as  this,  the  irrational 
is  recognized  by  the  side  of  and  in  the  rational.  In  this  case  the  irra- 
tional of  the  event  without  causal  compulsion  by  some  antecedent, 
or  of  the  self-determination  by  the  autonomous  idea  alone,  is  the  irra- 
tional of  freedom.     It  is  the  irrational  of  the  creative  procedure 


PSYCHOLOGY   IN   THE   SCIENCE   OF    RELIGION     285 

which  constitutes  the  idea  out  of  itself  and  produces  the  consequences 
of  the  reason  out  of  the  constituted  idea.  But  this  irrational  plays 
everywhere  in  the  whole  life  of  the  soul  an  essential  part,  and  is  not 
less  than  decisive  in  the  case  of  religion,  which  must  be  quite  differ- 
ent from  what  it  is  if  it  did  not  have  the  right  to  maintain  that 
which  it  declares  to  be  true  of  itself,  namely,  that  it  is  an  act  of 
freedom  and  a  gift  of  grace,  an  effect  of  the  supersensuous  permeating 
the  natural  phenomenal  life  of  the  soul  and  an  act  of  free  devotion 
the  natural  motivation. 

The  fourth  problem  arises,  when  we  examine  the  rational  law  of 
the  religious  nature  or  of  the  having  of  religion  which  lies  in  the 
being  and  organization  of  the  reason.  The  having  of  religion  may  be 
demonstrated  as  a  law  of  the  normal  consciousness  from  the  immanent 
feeling  of  necessity  and  obhgation  which  properly  belongs  to  religion, 
and  from  its  organic  place  in  the  economy  of  consciousness,  which 
receives  its  concentration  and  its  relation  to  an  objective  world- 
reason  only  from  religion.  But  precisely  because  religion  is  reduced 
to  this,  it  is  clear  that  this  is  only  a  reduction  which  abstracts  from 
the  empirical  actuality  just  as  the  categories  of  pure  reason  do.  This 
abstraction,  then,  should  under  no  circumstances  itself  be  regarded 
as  the  real  religion.  It  is  only  the  rational  a  priori  of  the  psychical 
appearances,  but  not  the  replacement  of  appearances  by  the  truth 
free  from  confusion.  The  psychical  reality  in  which  alone  the  truth 
is  effective  should  never  be  forgotten  out  of  regard  for  the  truth. 
This  is,  however,  the  fact  in  the  Kantian  theory  of  religion  in  two 
directions. 

It  is  always  noticeable  that  the  a  priori  of  the  practical  reason  is 
treated  by  Kant  quite  differently  from  the  theoretical.  In  case  of 
the  latter  the  main  idea  of  the  synthesis,  immanent  in  experience,  of 
rationalism  and  empiricism,  is  retained,  and  the  a  priori  of  the  pure 
forms  of  intuition  and  of  the  pure  categories  is  nothing  without  the 
contents  of  concrete  reality  which  become  shaped  in  it.  It  may  be 
very  difficult  actually  to  grasp  the  cooperation  of  the  a  priori  and 
the  empirical  in  the  single  case,  and  Kant's  theory  of  the  categories 
may  have  to  be  entirely  reshaped  and  approximated  to  a  priori 
hypotheses  requiring  verification,  but  the  principle  itself  is  always 
the  disposition  of  the  real  and  genuine  problem  of  all  knowledge.  In 
case  of  the  practical  a  priori  Kant  did,  it  is  true,  firmly  emphasize 
the  formal  character  of  the  ethical,  sesthetical,  and  religious  law, 
but,  in  doing  this,  does  not  lose  quite  out  of  sight  the  psychical 
reality.  They  appear  not  as  empty  forms  which  attain  to  their 
reality  only  when  filled  with  the  concrete  ethical  tasks,  the  artistic 
creations,  and  the  religious  states,  but  as  abstract  truths  of  reason, 
which  have  to  take  the  place  of  the  intricacies  of  usual  consciousness. 
A-t  this  point  one  has  always  been  right  in  feeling  a  relapse  on  the 


286  PHILOSOPHY   OF   RELIGION 

part  of  Kant  into  the  abstract,  analytical,  conceptual,  rationalism, 
and  for  this  very  reason  Kant's  statements  about  these  things  are 
of  great  sublimity  and  rigor  of  principle,  but  scanty  in  content.    It 
is  more  important  in  case  also  of  this  a  priori  of  the  practical  reason 
to  keep  in  mind  that  it  is  a  purely  formal  a  priori  and  in  reality 
must  constantly  be  in  relation  with  the  psychical  content,  in  order 
to  give  this  content  the  firm  core  of  the  real  and  the  principle  of 
the  critical  regulation  of  self.     So  the  a  priori  of  morals  is  not  to 
be  represented  abstractly  merely  by  itself,    but  it  is  to  be  con- 
ceived in  its  relation  to  all  the  tasks  which  we  feel  as  obligatory,  and 
it  extends  itself  from  that  point  outwards  over  the  total  expanse  of 
the  activity  of  reason.     Likewise  the  a  priori  of  art  is  not  to  be 
denoted  in  the  abstract  idea  of  the  unity  of  freedom  and  necessity, 
but  to  be  shown  in  the  whole  expanse  which  is  present  to  the  soul  as 
artistic  form  or  conception.    Thus,  in  especial  degree,  religion  is  not 
to  be  reduced  to  the  belief  of  reason  in  a  moral  world-order,  and 
simply  contrasted  with  all  supposed  religion  of  any  other  kind,  but 
the  religious  a  priori  should  only  serve  in  order  to  establish  the 
essential  in  the  empirical  appearance,  but  without  stripping  off  this 
appearance  altogether,  and  from  this  point  of  the  essential  to  correct 
the  intricacies  and  narrowness,  the  errors  and  false  combinations  of 
the  psychical  situation.   Kant,  by  his  original  thought  of  the  a  priori, 
was  urged  in  different  ways  to  such  a  view,  and  construed  epistemo- 
logically  the  empirical  psychological  religion  as  imaginary  illustra- 
tions of  the  a  priori.    But  that  is  occasional  only  and  does  not 
dominate  Kant's  real  view  of  religion.   This  is  and  still  remains  only  a 
translation  of  the  usual  moral  and  theological  rationalism  from  the 
formula  of  Locke  and  Wolff  into  the  formula  of  the  critical  philosophy. 
The  same  revision  occurs  in  quite  a  different  direction.   If  religion 
is  an  a  priori  of  reason,  it  is,  once  for  all,  established  together  with 
reason,  and  all  religion  is  everywhere  and  always  religious  in  the  same 
proposition  as  it  is  in  any  way  realized.    Schleiermacher  expressly 
stated  this  in  his  development  of  the  Kantian  theory,  and,  in  so  far 
as  the  practical  reason  is  always  penetrated  with  freedom,  and  con- 
sequently religion  itself  is  established  with  the  act  of  moral  freedom, 
this  was  also  asserted  by  Kant  himself.   Such  an  assertion,  however, 
contradicts  every  psychological  observation  whatsoever.    It  is  true 
such  observation  can  prove  that  religious  emotions  adjust  them- 
selves easily  to  all  activities  of  reason,  but  it  must  sharply  distin- 
guish what  is  nothing  more  than  the  religiousness  of  vague  feeling 
of  supersensual  regulations,  which  usually  are  joined  with  art  and 
morals,  from  real  and  characteristic  religiousness,  in  which,  each 
single  time,  a  purely  personal  relation  of  presence  to  the  super- 
sensuous  takes  place.    But  this  whole  problem  signifies  nothing  else 
than  the  actualizing  of  the  religious  a  priori,  which  actualizing 


PSYCHOLOGY  IN   THE  SCIENCE  OF  RELIGION    287 

always  occurs  in  quite  specific  and,  in  spite  of  all  difference,  essen- 
tially similar  psychical  experiences  and  states.    This  problem  of  the 
actualizing  of  the  religious  a  'priori  and  of  its  connection  with  con- 
crete individual  psychical  phenomena,  Kant  completely  overlooked 
in  his  abstract  concept  of  religion,  or  rather,  deliberately  ignored, 
because,  as  he  wrote  to  Jacobi,  he  saw  aU  the  dangers  of  mysticism 
lurking  in  it.   This  fear  was  justified;  for,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  all  the 
specific  occurrences  of  mysticism,  from  conversion,  prayer,  and  con- 
templation to  enthusiasm,  vision,  and  ecstasy,  do  lurk  in  it.     But 
without  this  mysticism  there  is  no  real  religion,  and  the  psychology 
of  religion  shows  most  clearly  how  the  real  pulse  of  religion  beats  in 
the  mystical  experiences.   A  religion  without  it  is  only  a  preliminary 
step,  or  a  reverberation  of  real  and  actual  religion.    Moreover,  the 
states  are  easily  conceived  in  a  theory  of  knowledge,  if  one  sees  in 
them  the  actualizing  of  the  religious  a  'priori,  the  production  of 
actual  religion  in  the  fusion  of  the  rational  law  with  the  concrete 
individual  psychical  fact.    The  mysticism  recognized  as  essential  by 
the  psychology  of  religion  must  find  its  place  in  the  theory  of  know- 
ledge, and  it  finds  it  as  the  psychological  actualizing  of  the  religious 
a  priori,  in  which  alone  that  interlacing  of  the  necessary,  the  rational, 
the  conformable  to  law,  and  the  factual  occurs,  which  characterizes 
real  religion.    The  dangers  of  such  a  mysticism,  which  are  recognized 
a  thousandfold  in  experience,  cannot  be  dispelled  altogether  by  the 
displacement  of  mysticism,  for  that  would  mean  to  displace  religion 
itself.    It  would  be  the  same,  if  one  should  try  to  avoid  the  dangers 
of  illusion  and  error,  by  keeping  to  the  pure  categories  alone,  and 
ceasing  to  employ  them  in  the  actual  thinking  of  experience.  Rather, 
they  can  be  dispelled  only  in  that  the  actualizing  of  the  rational 
a  priori  is  recognized  in  the  mystical  occurrences,  and  thus  the 
intricacies  and  one-sidedness  of  the  mere  psychological  stream  of 
religiousness  be  avoided.    The  psychological  reality  of  religion  must 
always  remember  the  rational  substance  of  religion,  and  always  bring 
religion  as  central  in  the  system  of  consciousness  into  fruitful  and 
adjusted  contact  with  the  total  life  of  the  reason.    Thus  the  psycho- 
logical reality  corrects  and  purifies  itself  out  of  its  own  a  priori,  with- 
out, however,  destroying  itself;  or  rather,  the  actual  religion  in  the 
psychical  category  of  the  mystical  occurrences  will  subside  to  a  more 
or  less  degree.  Thus  we  have  the  irrational  prevailing  here  in  its  third 
form,  which  like  the  two  others  was  contained  in  the  very  outset  of 
the  critical  system,  in  the  form  of  the  once-occurring,  factual,  and 
individual,  which,  of  course,  has  a  rational  basis  or  a  rational  element 
in  itself,  but  is  besides  a  pure  fact  and  reality.    Just  this  is  the 
excellence  of  the  rationalism  immanent  in  experience   (the  critical 
system) ,  that  it  makes  room  for  this  feature  beside  the  general  and 
conceptual  rationality.    It  did  not  make  room  for  it  to  the  extent 


288  PHILOSOPHY   OF   RELIGION 

really  required,  and  it  especially  left  no  space  for  it  in  its  abstract 
philosophy  of  religion.  This  space  must  again  be  opened  by  the 
theory  of  the  actualizing  of  the  religious  a  priori,  and  there  again 
lies  another  improvement  of  the  critical  system  under  the  influence  of 
modern  psychology. 

If  we  summarize  all  this,  we  have  a  quantity  of  concessions  by  the 
formal  epistemological  rationalism  to  the  irrationality  of  the  psycho- 
logical facts  and  a  repeated  breaking  down  of  the  over-rigorous 
Kantian  rationalism.  Contrariwise,  however,  the  pure  psychological 
investigation  is  also  compelled  to  withdraw  from  the  unlimited 
quantity  and  the  absolute  irrationality  of  the  multifarious  (and  of 
the  confusion  of  appearance  and  truth)  to  a  rational  criterium, 
which  can  be  found  in  the  rational  a  priori  of  the  reason  only,  and  in 
the  organic  position  of  this  a  priori  in  the  system  of  consciousness  in 
general.  By  this  rationalism  alone  may  the  true  validity  of  religion 
be  founded,  and  by  this  alone  the  uncultivated  psychical  life  may 
be  critically  regulated.  Religion  will  be  conceived  in  its  concrete 
vitality  and  not  mutilated;  it  will  constantly  be  brought  out  of  the 
jumble  of  its  distortions,  blendings,  one-sidedness,  narrowness,  and 
exuberance  back  again  to  its  original  content,  and  to  its  organic 
relations  to  the  totality  of  the  life  of  reason,  to  the  scientific  moral 
and  artistic  accomplishments.  That  is  everything  that  science  can 
do  for  it,  but  is  not  this  service  great  enough  and  indispensable 
enough  to  justify  the  work  of  such  a  science?  We  do  not  stop  with 
nothing  more  than  "varieties  of  religious  experience"  which  is  the 
result  of  James's  method;  but  neither  do  we  stop  with  nothing  more 
than  a  rational  idea  of  religion,  which  overpowers  experience,  as  was 
still  so  in  the  case  of  Kant.  But  we  must  learn  how  intimately  to 
combine  the  empirical  and  psychological  with  the  critical  and  norma- 
tive. The  ideas  of  Hume  and  of  Leibnitz  must  once  more  be  brought 
into  relation  with  the  continuations  of  Kant's  work,  and  the  com- 
bination of  the  Anglo-Saxon  sense  for  reality  with  the  German 
spirit  of  speculation  is  still  the  task  for  the  new  century  as  well  as 
for  the  century  past. 


SHORT  PAPERS 

A  short  paper  was  contributed  to  this  Section  by  Professor  Alexander  T. 
Ormond,  of  Princeton  University,  on  "Some  Roots  and  Factors  of  Religion." 
The  speaker  said  that  religion,  Uke  everything  else  human,  has  its  rise  in  man's 
experience.  It  has  also  doubtless  had  a  history  that  wiU  present  the  outlines  of 
a  development,  if  but  the  course  of  that  development  can  be  traced.  "  But  ux  the 
case  of  religion  our  theory  of  development  wiU  be  largely  qualified  by  our  judg- 
ment as  to  its  origin;  while,  regarding  origin  itself,  we  have  to  depend  on  hypo- 
theses constructed  from  our  more  or  less  imperfect  acquaintance  with  the  races, 
and  especially  the  savage  races,  of  the  present.  The  primitive  pre-rehgious  man 
is  a  construction  from  present  data,  and  wiU  always  remain  more  or  less  hypo- 
thetical. This  wiU  partially  explain,  and  at  the  same  time  partially  excuse,  what 
we  will  agree  is  the  unsatisfactory  character  of  the  anthropological  theories  as 
accounts  of  the  origin  of  rehgion.  But  there  are  other  reasons  for  this  partial 
failure  that  are  less  excusable.  One  of  these  is  the  rather  singular  failure  of  the 
leading  anthropologists,  in  dealing  with  the  origin  of  religion,  to  distinguish 
between  fundamental  and  merely  tributary  causes.  For  instance,  if  we  suppose 
that  man  has  m  some  way  come  into  possession  of  a  germ  of  religiousness,  many 
things  wiU  become  genuine  tributaries  to  its  development  that  when  urged  as 
explanations  of  the  germ  itself  would  be  obviously  futile.  There  must  be  a  cause 
for  the  pretty  general  failure  to  note  this  distinction  which  is  vital  to  rehgious 
theory,  and  I  am  convinced  that  the  prLacipal  cause  is  a  certain  lack  of  psycho- 
logical insight  and  of  philosopliical  grasp  in  deahng  with  the  problem  of  the  first 
data  and  primary  roots  of  religion  in  man's  nature. 

"In  the  first  place,  it  is  needful  in  deahng  with  the  rehgion  of  the  hypothetical 
man  that  we  should  have  some  idea  of  what  constitutes  religion  in  the  actual 
man.  Now,  back  of  aU  the  outward  maliifestations  of  religion,  wiU  stand  the 
religious  consciousness  of  the  man  and  the  cormnimity,  and  it  wiU  be  this  that  will 
determine  the  idea  of  religion  in  its  most  essential  form.  The  developed  idea 
of  religion,  therefore,  arising  out  of  this  germinal  impression,  would  take  the  form 
of  a  sense  (we  may  now  caU  it  concept)  of  relatedness  to  some  being  akin  to  man 
himself,  and  yet  transcending  him  in  some  real  though  imdetermined  respects. 
Anything  short  of  this  would,  I  think,  leave  rehgion  in  some  respects  unaccounted 
for;  while  anything  more  would  perhaps  exclude  some  genuine  manifestations  of 
religion. 

"  If  the  idea  of  religion  arises  out  of  an  impression,  then  it  will  not  be  possible 
to  deny  to  it  an  inteUectual  root.  I  make  this  statement  with  some  diffidence, 
because  if  I  do  not  misinterpret  them,  some  recent  psychologists  have  practically 
denied  the  intehectual  root  in  their  doctrine  that  religion  can  have  no  orig- 
inal intellectual  content.  If  I  am  not  further  misled,  however,  these  writers 
would  admit  that  a  content  is  achieved  bj^  the  symbohc  use  of  experience.  This 
is  perhaps  all  I  need  argue  for  here;  since  our  epistemology  is  teaching  us 
that  the  distinction  between  symbolism  and  perception  is  only  that  between  the 
direct  and  the  indirect;  while  here  it  is  clear  that  its  use  in  developing  the  signi- 
ficance of  the  religious  impression  would  have  all  the  directness  and,  therefore,  aU 
the  cogency  of  an  immediate  inference. 

"  Let  us  now  restore  the- intellectual  and  emotional  elements  of  religion  to  their 
place  in  a  sjmthesis;  we  wiU  then  have  a  concrete  religious  experience  out  of 
which  may  be  analyzed  at  least  two  fundamental  factors.  The  first  of  these  is 
what  we  may  call  the  personal  factor  in  religion.    We  are  treading  in  the  foot- 


290  PHILOSOPHY   OF   RELIGION 

steps  of  the  anthropologists  when  we  find  among  the  most  undeveloped  savages 
a  tendency  to  personify  the  objects  of  their  worship.  When  it  comes  to  the  ques- 
tion of  determining  the  role  that  tliis  personalizing  tendency  has  actually 
played  in  the  development  of  religion,  the  anthropologists  divide  into  two 
camps,  one  of  these,  led  by  Max  Miiller,  regarding  it  as  a  symbolic  interpretation 
put  upon  the  impression  of  some  great  natural  or  cosmic  object  or  phenomenon; 
while  others,  including  Herbert  Spencer  and  Mr.  Tylor,  prefer  to  seek  the  originals 
of  religion  in  ancestral  dream-images  and  ghostly  apparitions.  These  writers 
thus  start  with  completely  anthropomorphic  terms,  and  their  problem  is  to 
de-anthropomorphize  the  elements  to  the  extent  necessary  to  constitute  them  data 
of  religion.  The  second  factor  standing  over  against  the  personal,  as  its  opposite, 
is  that  of  transcendence.  By  transcendence  I  mean  that  deifying,  infinitating 
process  that  is  ever  working  contra  to  the  anthropomorphic  influence  in  the 
sphere  of  religious  conceptions.  The  School  of  Spencer  regard  this  as  the  only 
legitimate  tendency  in  religion.  We  do  not  argue  this  point  here,  but  agree  that 
it  is  as  legitimate  and  real  a  factor  as  that  of  personality.  The  root  of  this  factor, 
if  our  diagnosis  of  the  idea  of  religion  be  correct,  is  to  be  sought  in  the  original 
impression  of  religion,  and  it  no  doubt  has  its  origin  in  man's  feeling-reaction 
from  that  impression.  We  have  pointed  to  submission  as  one  of  the  religious 
emotions.  Now  submission  rests  on  some  deeper  feeling-attitude,  which  some 
have  translated  into  the  feeling  or  sense  of  dependence.  This,  however,  is  not 
adequate,  since  men  have  the  sense  of  social  dependence  on  finite  beings,  and  we 
have  it  with  reference  to  the  floor  we  are  standing  on.  Rather,  it  seems  to  me, 
we  must  translate  it  into  the  stronger  and  more  unconditional  feeling  of  help- 
lessness. One  real  ground  of  our  religious  consciousness  is  the  sense  or  feeling  of 
helplessness  toward  God;  the  sense  that  we  have  no  standing  in  being  as  against 
the  Deity.  This  radical  feeling  utters  itself  in  every  note  of  the  religious  scale, 
from  the  lowest  superstitious  terror  to  the  highest  mystical  self-annihilation. 

"  These  two  factors,  the  forces  of  personalization  and  transcendence,  are  in- 
separable. They  constitute  the  terms  of  a  dialectic  within  the  religious  con- 
sciousness by  virtue  of  which  in  one  phase  our  religious  conceptions  are  becoming 
ever  more  adequate  and  satisfying,  while  from  another  point  of  view  their  in- 
sufficiency grows  more  and  more  apparent.  And,  on  the  broader  field  of  religious 
history,  they  embody  themselves  in  a  law  of  tendency,  which  Spencer  has  only 
half -expressed,  by  virtue  of  which  the  objects  of  religion  are  on  one  hand  becoming 
ever  more  intelligible;  on  the  other,  ever  more  transcendent  of  our  conceptions." 


A  short  paper  was  read  by  Professor  F.  C.  French,  Professor  of  Pliilosophy  in 
the  University  of  Nebraska,  on  "The  Bearing  of  Certain  Aspects  of  the  Newer 
Psychology  on  the  Philosophy  of  Religion."    The  speaker  said  in  part: 

"  The  relation  of  science  to  religion  has  received,  to  be  sure,  much  study,  but 
to  most  minds  hitherto  this  has  meant  the  relation  of  only  the  physical  sciences  to 
religion.  The  older  psychology  was  largely  speculative  and  metaphysical  in 
character.  There  were,  of  course,  some  who  employed  the  empirical  method  in 
psychology,  but  they  were  so  far  from  comprehending  the  full  scope  of  mental 
phenomena  that,  at  best,  their  work  gave  the  promise  of  a  science  rather  than 
a  science  itself. 

It  is  not  the  fact  that  the  newer  psychology  takes  account  of  the  physiological 
conditions  of  mental  life;  it  is  not  the  fact  that  the  subject  is  now  pursued  in 
laboratories  with  instruments  of  precision,  that  gives  it  its  fuU  standing  as  a 
science :  it  is  much  more  the  fact  that  the  psychology  of  to-day  has  found  a  place 
in  the  natural  system  of  mental  things  for  those  strange  and  relativeh'^  unusual 
phenomena  of  consciousness  which  to  the  scientifically  minded  seemed  totally 
unreal  and  to  the  superstitious  manifestations  of  the  supernatural.  .  .  . 


SHORT   PAPERS  291 

"  In  showing  that  the  abnormal  can  be  explained  in  terms  of  the  normal, 
psychology  does  now  for  the  phenomena  of  mind  what  the  physical  sciences 
have  long  done  for  the  phenomena  of  nature.  .  .  . 

"  Psychology  as  a  science  postulates  the  reign  of  natural  law  in  the  subjective 
sphere  just  as  rigorously  as  physics  postulates  the  reign  of  law  in  the  objective 
sphere.   .   .   . 

"It  is  not  in  the  unusual  and  the  abnormal  that  the  reflective  mind  is  to  see 
God.  It  is  not  through  gaps  in  nature  that  we  are  to  get  glimpses  of  the  super- 
natural. Rather  is  it  in  the  very  nature  of  nature,  rational,  harmonious,  law- 
conforming,  subject  to  scientific  interpretation,  that  we  have  the  best  evidence 
that  the  world  is  made  mind- wise,  that  it  is  the  work  of  an  intelligent  mind,  that 
there  is  a  rational  spirit  at  the  core  of  the  universe. 

"  For  science  the  transcendent  does  not  enter  into  the  perceptual  realm  external 
or  internal.  It  is,  indeed,  hard  for  the  religious  mind  to  admit  this  fact  in  all 
its  fullness.  Until  it  does,  however,  religion  must  always  stand  more  or  less  in 
fear  of  science.  Once  give  up  the  perceptual,  in  all  its  bearings,  to  science,  and 
religion  will  find  that  it  has  lost  a  weak  support  only  to  gain  a  stronger  one. 
Ultimately,  I  believe,  we  shall  find  that  the  full  acceptance  of  science  in  the  mental 
domain  as  well  as  in  the  physical  will  strengthen  the  rational  grounds  of  theistic 
behef." 


SECTION   C  — LOGIC 


SECTION  C  — LOGIC 


{Hall  6,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:  Professor  George  M.  Duncan,  Yale  University. 
Speakers:   Professor  William  A.  Hammond,  Cornell  University. 

Professor  Frederick  J.  E.  Woodbridge,  Columbia  University. 
Secretary:  Dr.  W.  H.  Sheldon,  Columbia  University. 

The  Chairman  of  this  Section,  Professor  George  M.  Duncan,  Pro- 
fessor of  Logic  and  Mathematics  at  Yale  University,  in  introducing 
the  speakers  spoke  briefly  of  the  scope  and  importance  of  the  sub- 
ject assigned  to  the  Section;  expressed,  on  behalf  of  those  in  attend- 
ance, regret  at  the  inability  of  Professor  Wilhelm  Windelband  to 
be  present  and  take  part  in  the  work  of  the  Section,  as  had  been 
expected;  congratulated  the  Section  on  the  papers  to  be  presented 
and  the  speakers  who  were  to  present  them;  and  announced  the 
final  programme  of  the  Section. 


THE  RELATIONS   OF   LOGIC   TO   OTHER  DISCIPLINES 

BY    PROFESSOR    WILLIAM    A.  HAMMOND 

[William  Alexander  Hammond,  Assistant  Professor  of  Ancient  and  Medieval 
Philosophy  and  Esthetics,  Cornell  University,  b.  May  20,  1861,  New  Ath- 
ens, Ohio.  A.B.  Harvard,  1885;  Ph.D.  Leipzig,  1891.  Lecturer  on  Classics, 
King's  College,  Windsor,  N.  S.,  1885-88;  Secretary  of  the  University  Fac- 
ulty, Cornell;  Member  American  Psychological  Association,  American 
Philosophical  Association.  Author  of  The  Characters  of  Theophrastus, 
translated  with  Introduction  ;  Aristotle's  Psychology,  translated  with  Intro- 
duction.] 

In  1787;  in  the  preface  to  the  second  edition  of  the  Kr.  d.  r.  V.,  Kant 
wrote  the  following  words:  "That  logic,  from  the  earliest  times, 
has  followed  that  secure  method  "  (namely,  the  secure  method  of  a 
science  witnessed  by  the  unanimity  of  its  workers  and  the  stability 
of  its  results)  "  may  be  seen  from  the  fact  that  since  Aristotle  it  has 
not  had  to  retrace  a  single  step,  unless  we  choose  to  consider  as 
improvements  the  removal  of  some  unnecessary  subtleties,  or  the 
clearer  definition  of  its  matter,  both  of  which  refer  to  the  elegance 
rather  than  to  the  solidity  of  the  science.  It  is  remarkable,  also,  that 
to  the  present  day,  it  has  not  been  able  to  make  one  step  in  advance, 
so  that  to  all  appearances  it  may  be  considered  as  completed  and 
perfect.  If  some  modern  philosophers  thought  to  enlarge  it,  by 
introducing  psychological  chapters  on  the  different  faculties  of 
knowledge  (faculty  of  imagination,  wit,  etc.),  or  metaphysical  chapters 
on  the  origin  of  knowledge  or  different  degrees  of  certainty  accord- 
ing to  the  difference  of  objects  (idealism,  skepticism,  etc.),  or,  lastly, 
anthropological  chapters  on  prejudices,  their  causes  and  remedies, 
this  could  only  arise  from  their  ignorance  of  the  peculiar  nature  of 
logical  science.  We  do  not  enlarge,  but  we  only  disfigure  the  sciences, 
if  we  allow  their  respective  limits  to  be  confounded ;  and  the  limits 
of  logic  are  definitely  fixed  by  the  fact  that  it  is  a  science  which  has 
nothing  to  do  but  fully  to  exhibit  and  strictly  to  prove  the  formal 
rules  of  all  thought  (whether  it  be  a  priori  or  empirical,  whatever  be 
its  origin  or  its  object,  and  whateA^er  be  the  impediments,  accidental 
or  natural,  which  it  has  to  encounter  in  the  human  mind).  "  —  [Trans- 
lated by  Max  Miiller.]  Scarcely  more  than  half  a  century  after  the 
publication  of  this  statement  of  Kant's,  John  Stuart  Mill  (Intro- 
duction to  System  of  Logic)  wrote:  "There  is  as  great  diversity 
among  authors  in  the  modes  which  they  have  adopted  of  defining 
logic,  as  in  their  treatment  of  the  details  of  it.  This  is  what 
might  naturally  be  expected  on  any  subject  on  which  writers  have 
availed  themselves  of  the  same  language  as  a  means  of  delivering 
different  ideas.  .  .  .  This  diversity  is  not  so  much  an  evil  to  be 


RELATIONS   OF   LOGIC   TO   OTHER   DISCIPLINES    297 

complained  of,  as  an  inevitable,  and  in  some  degree  a  proper  result 
of  the  imperfect  state  of  those  sciences  "  (that  is,  of  logic,  jurispru- 
dence, and  ethics).  "It  is  not  to  be  expected  that  there  should  be 
agreement  about  the  definition  of  an3^thing,  until  there  is  agree- 
ment about  the  thing  itself."  This  remarkable  disparity  of  opinion 
is  due  partly  to  the  changes  in  the  treatment  of  logic  from  Kant  to 
Mill,  and  partly  to  the  fact  that  both  statements  are  extreme.  That 
the  science  of  logic  was  "completed  and  perfect"  in  the  time  of 
Kant  could  only  with  any  degree  of  accuracy  be  said  of  the  treat- 
ment of  syllogistic  proof  or  the  deductive  logic  of  Aristotle.  That 
the  diversity  was  so  great  as  pictured  by  Mill  is  not  historically 
exact,  but  could  be  said  only  of  the  new  epistemological  and  psycho- 
logical treatment  of  logic  and  not  of  the  traditional  formal  logic. 
The  confusion  in  logic  is  no  doubt  largely  due  to  disagreement  in 
the  delimitation  of  its  proper  territory  and  to  the  consequent  variety 
of  opinions  as  to  its  relations  to  other  disciplines.  The  rise  of  induct- 
ive logic,  coincident  with  the  rise  and  growth  of  physical  science 
and  empiricism,  forced  the  consideration  of  the  question  as  to  the 
relation  of  formal  thought  to  reality,  and  the  consequent  entangle- 
ment of  logic  in  a  triple  alliance  of  logic,  psychology,  and  meta- 
physics. How  logic  can  maintain  friendly  relations  with  both  of 
these  and  yet  avoid  endangering  its  territorial  integrity  has  not  been 
made  clear  by  logicians  or  psA^chologists  or  metaphysicians,  and 
that,  too,  in  spite  of  persistent  attempts  justly  to  settle  the  issue  as 
to  their  respective  spheres  of  influence.  Until  modern  logic  definitely 
settles  the  question  of  its  aims  and  legitimate  problems,  it  is  difficult 
to  see  how  any  agreement  can  be  reached  as  to  its  relation  to  the 
other  disciplines.  The  situation  as  it  confronts  one  in  the  discus- 
sion of  the  relations  of  logic  to  allied  subjects  may  be  analyzed  as 
follows : 

1.  The  relation  of  logic  as  science  to  logic  as  art. 

2.  The  relation  of  logic  to  psychology. 

3.  The  relation  of  logic  to  metaphysics. 

The  development  of  nineteenth  century  logic  has  made  an  answer  to 
the  last  two  of  the  foregoing  problems  exceedingly  difficult.  Indeed, 
one  may  say  that  the  evolution  of  modern  epistemology  has  had  a 
centrifugal  influence  on  logic,  and  instead  of  growth  towards  unity 
of  conception  we  have  a  chaos  of  diverse  and  discordant  theories. 
The  apple  of  discord  has  been  the  theory  of  knowledge.  A  score  of 
years  ago  when  Adamson  wrote  his  admirable  article  in  the  Ency- 
clopcedia  Britannica  (article  ''Logic,"  1882),  he  found  the  conditions 
much  the  same  as  I  now  find  them.  "  Looking  to  the  chaotic  state  of 
logical  text-books  at  the  present  time,  one  would  be  inclined  to  say 
that  there  does  not  exist  anywhere  a  recognized  currently  received 
body  of  speculations  to  which  the  title  logic  can  be  unambiguously 


298  LOGIC 

assigned,  and  that  we  must  therefore  resign  the  hope  of  attaining 
by  any  empirical  consideration  of  the  received  doctrine  a  precise 
determination  of  the  nature  and  Umits  of  logical  theory."  I  do  not, 
however,  take  quite  so  despondent  a  view  of  the  logical  chaos  as 
the  late  Professor  Adamson;  rather,  I  believe  with  Professor  Stratton 
(Psy.  Rev.  vol.  iii)  that  something  is  to  be  gained  for  unity  and 
consistency  by  more  exact  delimitation  of  the  subject-matter  of 
the  philosophical  disciplines  and  their  interrelations,  which  pre- 
cision, if  secured,  would  assist  in  bringing  into  clear  relief  the  real 
problems  of  the  several  departments  of  inquiry,  and  facihtate  the 
proper  classification  of  the  disciplines  themselves. 

The  attempt  to  delimit  the  spheres  of  the  disciplines,  to  state  their 
interrelations  and  classify  them,  was  made  early  in  the  history  of 
philosophy,  at  the  very  beginning  of  the  development  of  logic  as 
a  science  by  Aristotle.  In  Plato's  philosophy,  logic  is  not  separated 
from  epistemology  and  metaphysics.  The  key  to  his  metaphysics  is 
given  essentially  in  his  theory  of  the  reality  of  the  concept,  which 
offers  an  interesting  analogy  to  the  position  of  logic  in  modern 
idealism.  Before  Plato  there  was  no  formulation  of  logical  theory, 
and  in  his  dialogues  it  is  only  contained  in  solution.  The  nearest 
approach  to  any  formulation  is  to  be  found  in  an  applied  logic  set 
forth  in  the  precepts  and  rules  of  the  rhetoricians  and  sophists. 
Properly  speaking,  Aristotle  made  the  first  attempt  to  define  the 
subject  of  logic  and  to  determine  its  relations  to  the  other  sciences. 
In  a  certain  sense  logic  for  Aristotle  is  not  a  science  at  all.  For 
science  is  concerned  with  some  ens,  some  branch  of  reality,  while 
logic  is  concerned  with  the  methodology  of  knowing,  with  the 
formal  processes  of  thought  whereby  an  ens  or  a  reality  is  ascertained 
and  appropriated  to  knowledge.  In  the  sense  of  a  method  whereby 
all  scientific  knowledge  is  secured,  logic  is  a  propaedeutic  to  the 
sciences.  In  the  idealism  of  the  Eleatics  and  Plato,  thought  and  being 
are  ultimately  identical,  and  the  laws  of  thought  are  the  laws  of 
being.  In  Aristotle's  conception,  while  the  processes  of  thought 
furnish  a  knowledge  of  reality  or  being,  their  formal  operation  con- 
stitutes the  technique  of  investigation,  and  their  systematic  explana- 
tion and  description  constitute  logic.  Logic  and  metaphysics  are  dis- 
tinguished as  the  science  of  being  and  the  doctrine  of  the  thought- 
processes  whereby  being  is  known.  Logic  is  the  doctrine  of  the 
organon  of  science,  and  when  applied  is  the  organon  of  science.  The 
logic  of  Aristotle  is  not  a  purely  formal  logic.  He  is  not  interested  in 
the  merely  schematic  character  of  the  thought-processes,  but  in 
their  function  as  mediators  of  apodictic  truth.  He  begins  with  the 
assumption  that  in  the  conjunction  and  disjunction  of  correctly 
formed  judgments  the  conjunction  or  disjunction  of  reality  is  mir- 
rored.   Aristotle  does  not  here  examine  into  the  powers  of  the  mind 


RELATIONS   OF   LOGIC  TO   OTHER   DISCIPLINES   299 

as  a  whole;  that  is  done,  though  fragmentarily,  in  the  De  Anima  and 
Parva  Naturalia,  where  the  mental  powers  are  regarded  as  phases  of 
the  processes  of  nature  without  reference  to  normation;  but  in  his  logic 
he  inquires  only  into  those  forms  and  laws  of  thinking  which  mediate 
proof.  Scientific  proof,  in  his  conception,  is  furnished  in  the  form  of 
the  syllogism,  whose  component  elements  are  terms  and  propositions. 
In  the  little  tract  On  Interpretation  (i.  e.  on  the  judgment  as  inter- 
preter of  thought),  if  it  is  genuine,  the  proposition  is  considered  in 
its  logical  bearing.  The  treatise  on  the  Categories,  which  discusses 
the  nature  of  the  most  general  terms,  forms  a  connecting  link  be- 
tween logic  and  metaphysics.  The  categories  are  the  most  general 
concepts  or  universal  modes  under  which  we  have  knowledge  of 
the  world.  They  are  not  simply  logical  relations;  they  are  existential 
forms,  being  not  only  the  modes  under  which  thought  regards  being, 
but  the  modes  under  which  being  exists.  Aristotle's  theory  of  the 
methodology  of  science  is  intimately  connected  with  his  view  of 
knowledge.  Scientific  knowledge  in  his  opinion  refers  to  the  essence 
of  things;  for  example,  to  those  universal  aspects  of  reality  which 
are  given  in  particulars,  but  which  remain  self-identical  amidst  the 
variation  and  passing  of  particulars.  The  universal,  however,  is 
knoAvn  only  through  and  after  particulars.  There  is  no  such  thing 
as  innate  knowledge  or  Platonic  reminiscence.  Knowledge,  if  not 
entirely  empirical,  has  its  basis  in  empirical  reality.  Causes  are 
known  only  through  effects.  The  universals  have  no  existence  apart 
from  things,  although  they  exist  realiter  in  things.  Empirical  know- 
ledge of  particulars  must,  therefore,  precede  in  time  the  conceptual 
or  scientific  knowledge  of  universals.  In  the  evolution  of  scientific 
knowledge  in  the  individual  mind,  the  body  of  particulars  or  of 
sense-experience  is  to  its  conceptual  transformation  as  potentiality 
is  to  actuality,  matter  to  form,  the  completed  end  of  the  former 
being  realized  in  the  latter.  Only  in  the  sense  of  this  power  to  trans- 
form and  conceptualize,  does  the  mind  have  knowledge  within  itself. 
The  genetic  content  is  experiential;  the  developed  concept,  judg- 
ment, or  inference  is  in  form  noetic.  Knowledge  is,  therefore,  not 
a  mere  "precipitate  of  experience,"  nor  is  Aristotle  a  complete 
empiricist.  The  conceptual  form  of  knowledge  is  not  immediately 
given  in  things  experienced,  but  is  a  product  of  noetic  discrimination 
and  combination.  Of  a  sensible  object  as  such  there  is  no  concept; 
the  object  of  a  concept  is  the  generic  essence  of  a  thing;  and  the 
concept  itself  is  the  thought  of  this  generic  essence.  The  individual 
is  generalized;  every  concept  does  or  can  embrace  several  individuals. 
It  is  an  "  aggregate  of  distinguishing  marks, "  and  is  expressed  in  a 
definition.  The  concept  as  such  is  neither  true  nor  false.  Truth  first 
arises  in  the  form  of  a  judgment  or  proposition,  wherein  a  subject 
is  coupled  with  a  predicate,  and  something  is  said  about  something. 


300  LOGIC 

A  Judgment  is  true  when  the  thought  (whose  inward  process  is  the 
judgment  and  the  expression  in  vocal  symbols  is  the  proposition) 
regards  as  conjoined  or  divided  that  which  is  conjoined  or  divided 
in  actuality;  in  other  words,  when  the  thought  is  congruous  with 
the  real.     While  Aristotle  does  not  ignore  induction  as  a  scientific 
method,  (how  could  he  when  he  regards  the  self-subsistent  individual 
as  the  only  real?)  yet  he  says  that,  as  a  method,  it  labors  under 
the  defect  of  being  only  proximate;  a  complete  induction  from  all 
particulars  is  not  possible,  and  therefore  cannot  furnish  demonstra- 
tion.    Only  the  deductive  process  proceeding  syllogistically  from 
the  universal  (or  essential  truth)  to  the  particular  is  scientifically 
cogent  or  apodictic.    Consequently  Aristotle  developed  the  science 
of  logic  mainly  as  a  syllogistic  technique  or  instrument  of  demon- 
stration.   From  this  brief  sketch  of  Aristotle's  logical  views  it  will 
be  seen  that  the  epistemological   and    metaphysical    relations    of 
logic  which  involve  its  greatest  difficulty  and  cause  the  greatest 
diversity  in  its  modern   exponents,  were   present   in   undeveloped 
form  to  the  mind  of  the  first  logician.    It  would  require  a  mighty 
optimism  to  suppose  that  this  difficulty  and  diversity,  which  has 
increased  rather  than  diminished  in  the  progress  of  historical  philo- 
sophy, should  suddenly  be  made  to  vanish  by  some  magic  of  re- 
statement  of   subject-matter,   or   theoretical   delimitation   of   the 
discipline.    As  Fichte  said  of  philosophy,  "  The  sort  of  a  philosophy 
that  a  man  has,  depends  on  the  kind  of  man  he  is; "  so  one  might 
almost  say  of  logic,  "The  sort  of  logic  that  a  man  has,  depends  on 
the  kind  of  philosopher  he  is."    If  the  blight  of  discord  is  ever  re- 
moved from  epistemology,  we  may  expect  agreement  as  to  the  rela- 
tions of  logic  to  metaphysics.    Meanwhile  logic  has  the  great  body 
of  scientific  results  deposited  in  the  physical  sciences  on  which  to 
build  and  test,  with  some  assurance,  its  doctrine  of  methodology; 
and  as  philosophy  moves  forward  persistently  to  the  final  solution 
of  its  problems,  logic  may  justly  expect  to  be  a  beneficiary  in  its 
established  theories. 

After  Aristotle's  death  logic  lapsed  into  a  formalism  more  and 
more  removed  from  any  vital  connection  with  reality  and  oblivious 
to  the  profound  epistemological  and  methodological  questions  that 
Aristotle  had  at  least  raised.  In  the  Middle  Ages  it  became  a  highly 
developed  exercise  in  inference  applied  to  the  traditional  dogmas  of 
theology  and  science  as  premises,  with  mainly  apologetic  or  polemi- 
cal functions.  Its  chief  importance  is  found  in  its  application  to  the 
problem  of  realism  and  nominalism,  the  question  as  to  the  nature  of 
universals.  At  the  height  of  scholasticism  realism  gained  its  victory 
by  syllogistically  showing  the  congruity  of  its  premises  with  certain 
fundamental  dogmas  of  the  Church,  especially  with  the  dogma  of  the 
unity  and  reality  of  the  Godhead.  The  heretical  conclusion  involved 


RELATIONS   OF  LOGIC  TO   OTHER  DISCIPLINES   301 

in  nominalism  is  equivalent  (the  accepted  dogma  of  the  Church  be- 
ing axiomatic)  to  reductio  ad  ahsurdum.  A  use  of  logic  such  as  this, 
tending  to  conserve  rather  than  to  increase  the  body  of  knowledge, 
was  bound  to  meet  with  attack  on  the  awakening  of  post-renaissance 
interest  in  the  physical  world,  and  the  acquirement  of  a  body  of  truth 
to  which  the  scholastic  formal  logic  had  no  relation.  The  anti-scholas- 
tic movement  in  logic  was  inaugurated  by  Francis  Bacon,  who 
sought  in  his  Novum  Organum  to  give  science  a  real  content  through 
the  application  of  induction  to  experience  and  the  discovery  of 
universal  truths  from  particular  instances.  The  syllogism  is  rejected 
as  a  scientific  instrument,  because  it  does  not  lead  to  principles,  but 
proceeds  only  from  principles,  and  is  therefore  not  useful  for  dis- 
covery. It  permits  at  most  only  refinements  on  knowledge  already 
possessed,  but  cannot  be  regarded  as  creative  or  productive.  The 
Baconian  theory  of  induction  regarded  the  accumulation  of  facts 
and  the  derivation  of  general  principles  and  laws  from  them  as  the 
true  and  fruitful  method  of  science.  In  England  this  empirical  view 
of  logic  has  been  altogether  dominant,  and  the  most  illustrious  Eng- 
lish exponents  of  logical  theory,  Herschel,  Whewell,  and  Mill, 
have  stood  on  that  ground.  Since  the  introduction  of  German 
idealism  in  the  last  half  century  a  new  logic  has  grown  up  whose 
chief  business  is  with  the  theory  of  knowledge. 

Kant's  departure  in  logic  is  based  on  an  epistemological  examin- 
ation of  the  nature  of  judgment,  and  on  the  answer  to  his  own 
question,  "How  are  synthetic  judgments  a  priori  possible?"  The 
a  priori  elements  in  knowledge  make  knowledge  of  the  real  nature  of 
things  impossible.  Human  knowledge  extends  to  the  phenomenal 
world,  which  is  seen  under  the  a  priori  forms  of  the  understanding. 
Logic  for  Kant  is  the  science  of  the  formal  and  necessary  laws  of 
thought,  apart  from  any  reference  to  objects.  Pure  or  universal 
logic  aims  to  understand  the  forms  of  thought  without  regard  to  meta- 
physical or  psychological  relations,  and  this  position  of  Kant  is  the 
historical  beginning  of  the  subjective  formal  logic. 

In  the  metaphysical  logic  of  Hegel,  which  rests  on  a  panlogistic 
basis,  being  and  thought,  form  and  content,  are  identical.  Logical 
necessity  is  the  measure  and  criterion  of  objective  reality.  The  body 
of  reality  is  developed  through  the  dialectic  self-movement  of  the 
idea.  In  such  an  idealistic  monism,  formal  and  real  logic  are  by  the 
metaphysical  postulate  coincident. 

Schleiermacher  in  his  dialectic  regards  logic  from  the  standpoint 
of  epistemological  realism,  in  which  the  real  deliverances  of  the 
senses  are  conceptually  transformed  by  the  spontaneous  activity 
of  reason.  This  spirit  of  reahsm  is  similar  to  that  of  Aristotle,  in  which 
the  one-sided  a  priori  view  of  knowledge  is  controverted.  Space  and 
time  are  forms  of  the  existence  of  things,  and  not  merely  a  priori 


302  LOGIC 

forms  of  knowing.  Logic  he  divides  into  dialectic  and  technical 
logic.  The  former  regards  the  idea  of  knowledge  as  such;  the  formal 
or  technical  regards  knowledge  in  the  process  of  becoming  or  the 
idea  of  knowledge  in  motion.  The  forms  of  this  process  are  induction 
and  deduction.  The  Hegelian  theory  of  the  generation  of  knowledge 
out  of  the  processes  of  pure  thought  is  emphatically  rejected, 

Lotze,  who  is  undoubtedly  one  of  the  most  influential  and  fruitful 
writers  on  logic  in  the  last  century,  attempts  to  bring  logic  into 
closer  relations  with  contemporary  science,  and  is  an  antagonist  of 
one-sided  formal  logics.  For  him  logic  falls  into  the  three  parts  of 
(1)  pure  logic  or  the  logic  of  thought;  (2)  applied  logic  or  the  logic 
of  investigation;  (3)  the  logic  of  knowledge  or  methodology;  and  this 
classification  of  the  matter  and  problems  of  logic  has  had  an  im- 
portant influence  on  subsequent  treatises  on  the  discipline.  His 
logic  is  formal,  as  he  describes  it  himself,  in  the  sense  of  setting  forth 
the  modes  of  the  operation  of  thought  and  its  logical  structure;  it  is 
real  in  the  sense  that  these  forms  are  dependent  on  the  nature  of 
things  and  not  something  independently  given  in  the  mind.  While 
he  aims  to  maintain  the  distinct  separation  of  logic  and  metaphysics, 
he  says  (in  the  discussion  of  the  relations  between  formal  and  real 
logical  meaning)  the  question  of  meaning  naturally  raises  a  meta- 
physical problem:  "  Ich  thue  besser  der  Metaphysik  die  weitere 
Erorterung  dieses  wichtigen  Punktes  zu  iiberlassen."  {Log.  2d  ed. 
p.  571.)  How  could  it  be  otherwise  when  his  whole  view  of  the  rela- 
tions and  validity  of  knowledge  is  inseparable  from  his  realism  or 
teleological  idealism,  as  he  himself  characterizes  his  own  standpoint? 

Drobisch,  a  follower  of  Herbart,  is  one  of  the  most  thoroughgoing 
formalists  in  modern  logical  theory.  He  attempts  to  maintain  strictly 
the  distinction  between  thought  and  knowledge.  Logic  is  the  science 
of  thought.  He  holds  that  there  may  be  formal  truth,  for  example, 
logically  valid  truth,  which  is  materially  false.  Logic,  in  other  words, 
is  purely  formal;  material  truth  is  matter  for  metaphysics  or  science. 
Drobisch  holds,  therefore,  that  the  falsity  of  the  judgment  expressed 
in  the  premise  from  which  a  formally  correct  syllogism  may  be  deduced, 
is  not  subject-matter  for  logic.  The  sphere  of  logic  is  limited  to  the 
region  of  inference  and  forms  of  procedure,  his  view  of  the  nature 
and  function  of  logic  being  determined  largely  by  the  bias  of  his 
mathematical  standpoint.  The  congruity  of  thought  with  itself, 
judgments,  conclusions,  analyses,  etc.,  is  the  sole  logical  truth,  as 
against  Trendelenburg,  who  took  the  Aristotelian  position  that  log- 
ical truth  is  the  "agreement  of  thought  with  the  object  of  thought." 

Sigwart  looks  at  logic  mainly  from  the  standpoint  of  the  tech- 
nology of  science,  in  which,  however,  he  discovers  the  implications 
of  a  teleological  metaphysic.  Between  the  processes  of  conscious- 
ness and  external  changes  he  finds  a  causal  relation  and  not  parallel- 


RELATIONS   OF   LOGIC   TO  OTHER   DISCIPLINES    303 

ism.  Inasmuch  as  thought  sometimes  misses  its  aim,  as  is  shown 
by  the  fact  that  error  and  dispute  exist,  there  is  need  of  a  discipline 
whose  purpose  is  to  show  us  how  to  attain  and  estabhsh  truth  and 
avoid  error.  This  is  the  practical  aim  of  logic,  as  distinguished  from 
the  psychological  treatment  of  thought,  where  the  distinction  between 
true  and  false  has  no  more  place  than  the  distinction  between  good 
and  bad.  Logic  presupposes  the  impulse  to  discover  truth,  and  it 
therefore  sets  forth  the  criteria  of  true  thinking,  and  endeavors 
to  describe  those  normative  operations  whose  aim  is  validity  of 
judgment.  Consequently  logic  falls  into  the  two  parts  of  (1)  critical, 
(2)  technical,  the  former  having  meaning  only  in  reference  to  the 
latter;  the  main  value  of  logic  is  to  be  sought  in  its  function  as  art. 
''Methodology,  therefore,  which  is  generally  made  to  take  a  subor- 
dinate place,  should  be  regarded  as  the  special,  final,  and  chief  aim  of 
our  science."  (Logic,  vol.  i,  p.  21,  Eng.  Tr.)  As  an  art,  logic  under- 
takes to  determine  under  what  conditions  and  prescriptions  judgments 
are  valid,  but  does  not  undertake  to  pass  upon  the  validity  of  the  con- 
tent of  given  judgments.  Its  prescriptions  have  regard  only  to  formal 
correctness  and  not  to  the  material  truth  of  results.  Logic  is,  there- 
fore, a  formal  discipline.  Its  business  is  with  the  due  procedure  of 
thought,  and  it  attempts  to  show  no  more  than  how  we  may  advance 
in  the  reasoning  process  in  such  way  that  each  step  is  valid  and 
necessary.  If  logic  were  to  tell  us  what  to  think  or  give  us  the  con- 
tent of  thought,  it  would  be  commensurate  with  the  whole  of  science. 
Sigwart,  however,  does  not  mean  by  formal  thought  independence  of 
content,  for  it  is  not  possible  to  disregard  the  particular  manner  in 
which  the  materials  and  content  of  thought  are  delivered  through 
sensation  and  formed  into  ideas.  Further,  logic  having  for  its  chief 
business  the  methodology  of  science,  the  development  of  knowledge 
from  empirical  data,  it  ought  to  include  a  theory  of  knowledge,  but 
it  should  not  so  far  depart  from  its  subjective  limits  as  to  include 
within  its  province  the  discussion  of  metaphysical  implications  or 
a  theory  of  being.  For  this  reason,  Sigwart  relegates  to  a  postscript 
his  discussion  of  teleology,  but  he  gives  an  elaborate  treatment  of 
epistemology  extending  through  vol.  i  and  develops  his  account  of 
methodology  in  vol.  ii.  The  question  regarding  the  relation  between 
necessity,  the  element  in  which  logical  thought  moves,  and  freedom, 
the  postulate  of  the  will,  carries  one  beyond  the  confines  of  logic  and 
is,  in  his  opinion,  the  profoundest  problem  of  metaphysics,  whose 
function  is  to  deal  with  the  ultimate  relation  between  "subject 
and  object,  the  world'  and  the  individual,  and  this  is  not  only  basal 
for  logic  and  all  science,  but  is  the  crown  and  end  of  them  all." 

Wundt's  psychological  and  methodological  treatment  of  logic 
stands  midway  between  the  purely  formal  treatises  on  the  one  hand , 
and  the  metaphysical  treatises  on  the  other  hand.     The  general 


304  LOGIC 

standpoint  of  Wundt  is  similar  to  that  of  Sigwart,  in  that  he  dis- 
covers the  function  of  logic  in  the  exposition  of  the  formation  and 
methods  of  scientific  knowledge;  for  example,  in  epistemology  and 
methodology.  Logic  must  conform  to  the  conditions  under  which 
scientific  inquiry  is  actually  carried  on;  the  forms  of  thought, 
therefore,  cannot  be  separate  from  or  indifferent  to  the  content  of 
knowledge;  for  it  is  a  fundamental  principle  of  science  that  its 
particular  methods  are  determined  by  the  nature  of  its  particular 
subject-matter.  Scientific  logic  must  reject  the  theory  that  identifies 
thought  and  being  (Hegel)  and  the  theory  of  parallelism  between 
thought  and  reality  (Schleiermacher,  Trendelenburg,  and  Ueberweg), 
in  which  the  ultimate  identity  of  the  two  is  only  concealed.  Both 
of  these  theories  base  logic  on  a  metaphysics,  which  makes  it  nec- 
essary to  construe  the  real  in  terms  of  thought,  and  logic,  so  di- 
vorced from  empirical  reality,  is  powerless  to  explain  the  methods  of 
scientific  procedure.  One  cannot,  however,  avoid  the  acceptance  of 
thought  as  a  competent  organ  for  the  interpretation  of  reality,  unless 
one  abandons  all  question  of  validity  and  accepts  agnosticism  or 
skepticism.  This  interpretative  power  of  thought  or  congruity  with 
reality  is  translated  by  metaphysical  logic  into  identity.  Metaphysical 
logic  concerns  itself  fundamentally  with  the  content  of  knowledge,  not 
with  its  evidential  or  formal  logical  aspects,  but  with  being  and  the 
laws  of  being.  It  is  the  business  of  metaphysics  to  construct  its 
notions  and  theories  of  reality  out  of  the  deliverances  of  the  special 
sciences  and  inferences  derived  therefrom.  The  aim  of  metaphysics 
is  the  development  of  a  world-view  free  from  internal  contradictions, 
a  view  that  shall  unite  all  particular  and  plural  knowledges  into  a 
whole.  Logic  stands  in  more  intimate  relation  to  the  special  sciences, 
for  here  the  relations  are  reciprocal  and  immediate;  for  example, 
from  actual  scientific  procedure  logic  abstracts  its  general  laws  and 
results,  and  these  in  turn  it  delivers  to  the  sciences  as  their  formu- 
lated methodology.  In  the  history  of  science  the  winning  of  know- 
ledge precedes  the  formulation  of  the  rules  employed,  that  is,  pre- 
cedes any  scientific  methodology.  Logic,  as  methodology,  is  not  an 
a  priori  construction,  but  has  its  genesis  in  the  growth  of  science 
itself  and  in  the  discovery  of  those  tests  and  criteria  of  truth  which 
are  found  to  possess  an  actual  heuristic  or  evidential  value.  It  is 
not  practicable  to  separate  epistemology  and  logic,  for  such  con- 
cepts as  causality,  analogy,  validity,  etc.,  are  fundamental  in  logical 
method,  and  yet  they  belong  to  the  territory  of  epistemology,  are 
epistemological  in  nature,  as  one  may  indeed  say  of  all  the  general 
law^s  of  thought.  A  formal  logic  that  is  merely  propaedeutic,  a  logic  that 
aims  to  free  itself  from  the  quarrels  of  epistemology,  is  scientifically 
useless.  Its  norms  are  valueless,  in  so  far  as  they  can  only  teach  the 
arrangement  of  knowledge  already  possessed,  and  teach  nothing  as  to 


RELATIONS   OF  LOGIC  TO   OTHER   DISCIPLINES  305 

how  to  secure  it  or  test  its  real  validity.  While  formal  logic  aims  to 
put  itself  outside  of  philosophy,  metaphysical  logic  would  usurp 
the  place  of  philosoph3^  Formal  logic  is  inadequate,  because  it 
neither  shows  how  the  laws  of  thought  originate,  why  they  are 
valid,  nor  in  what  sense  they  are  applicable  to  concrete  investigation. 
Wundt,  therefore,  develops  a  logic  which  one  may  call  epistemo- 
logical  methodological,  and  which  stands  between  the  extremes  of 
formal  logic  and  metaphysical  logic.  The  laws  of  logic  must  be 
derived  from  the  processes  of  psychic  experience  and  the  procedure 
of  the  sciences.  "Logic  therefore  needs,"  as  he  says,  ''epistemology 
for  its  foundation  and  the  doctrine  of  methods  for  its  completion." 

Lipps  takes  the  view  outright  that  logic  is  a  branch  of  psychology; 
Husserl  in  his  latest  book  goes  to  the  other  extreme  of  a  purely 
formal  and  technical  logic,  and  devotes  almost  his  entire  first  volume 
to  the  complete  sundering  of  psj^chology  and  logic. 

Bradley  bases  his  logic  on  the  theory  of  the  judgment.  The  logical 
judgment  is  entirely  different  from  the  psychological.  The  logical 
judgment  is  a  qualification  of  reality  by  means  of  an  idea.  The 
predicate  is  an  adjective  or  attribute  which  in  the  judgment  is 
ascribed  to  reality.  The  aim  of  truth  is  to  qualify  reality  by  general 
notions.  But  inasmuch  as  reality  is  individual  and  self-existent, 
whereas  truth  is  universal,  truth  and  reality  are  not  coincident. 
Bradley's  metaphysical  solution  of  the  disparity  between  thought 
and  reality  is  put  forward  in  his  theory  of  the  unitary  Absolute, 
whose  concrete  content  is  the  totality  of  experience.  But  as  thought 
is  not  the  whole  of  experience,  judgments  cannot  compass  the  whole 
of  reality.  Bosanquet  objects  to  this,  and  maintains  that  reality  must 
not  be  regarded  as  an  ideal  construction.  The  real  world  is  the  world  to 
which  our  concepts  and  judgments  refer.  In  the  former  we  have  a 
world  of  isolated  individuals  of  definite  content;  in  the  latter,  we  have 
a  world  of  definitely  systematized  and  organized  content.  Under  the 
title  of  the  Morphology  of  Knowledge  Bosanquet  considers  the  evo- 
lution of  judgment  and  inference  in  their  varied  forms.  "  Logic  starts 
from  the  individual  mind,  as  that  within  which  we  have  the  actual 
facts  of  intelligence,  which  we  are  attempting  to  interpret  into  a  sys- 
tem "  {Logic,  vol.  I,  p.  247).  The  real  world  for  every  individual  is  his 
world.  "The  work  of  intellectually  constituting  that  totality  which 
we  call  the  real  world  is  the  work  of  knowledge.  The  work  of  analyz- 
ing the  process  of  this  constitution  or  determination  is  the  work  of 
logic,  which  might  be  described  ...  as  the  reflection  of  knowledge 
upon  itself  "  (Logic,  vol.  i,  p.  3).  "The  relation  of  logic  to  truth  con- 
sists in  examining  the  characteristics  by  which  the  various  phases 
of  the  one  intellectual  function  are  fitted  for  their  place  in  the 
intellectual  totality  which  constitutes  knowledge  "  (ibid.).  The  real 
world  is  the  intelligible  world ;  reality  is  something  to  which  we  attain 


306  LOGIC 

by  a  constructive  process.  We  have  here  a  type  of  logic  which  is 
essentially  a  metaphysic.  Indeed,  Bosanquet  says  in  the  course  of  his 
first  volume :  "  I  entertain  no  doubt  that  in  content  logic  is  one  with 
metaphysics,  and  differs,  if  at  all,  simply  in  mode  of  treatment  —  in 
tracing  the  evolution  of  knowledge  in  the  light  of  its  value  and  import, 
instead  of  attempting  to  summarize  its  value  and  import  apart  from 
the  details  of  its  evolution  "  {Logic,  vol.  i,  247). 

Dewey  (Studies  in  Logical  Theory,  p.  5)  describes  the  essential 
function  of  logic  as  the  inquiry  into  the  relations  of  thought  as  such 
to  reality  as  such.  Although  such  an  inquiry  may  involve  the  investi- 
gation of  psychological  processes  and  of  the  concrete  methods  of 
science  and  verification,  a  description  and  analysis  of  the  forms  of 
thought,  conception,  judgment,  and  inference,  yet  its  concern  with 
these  is  subordinate  to  its  main  concern,  namely,  the  relation  of 
"thought  at  large  to  reality  at  large."  Logic  is  not  reflection  on 
thought,  either  on  its  nature  as  such  or  on  its  forms,  but  on  its  relations 
to  the  real.  In  Dewey's  philosophy,  logical  theory  is  a  description  of 
thought  as  a  mode  of  adaptation  to  its  own  conditions,  and  validity 
is  judged  in  terms  of  the  efficiency  of  thought  in  the  solution  of  its 
own  problems  and  difficulties.  The  problem  of  logic  is  more  than 
epistemological.  Wherever  there  is  striving  there  are  obstacles ;  and 
wherever  there  is  thinking  there  is  a  "  material-in-question."  Dewey's 
logic  is  a  theory  of  reflective  experience  regarded  functionally,  or 
a  pragmatic  view  of  the  discipline.  This  logic  of  experience  aims  to 
evaluate  the  signiflcance  of  social  research,  psychology,  fine  and  in- 
dustrial art,  and  religious  aspiration  in  the  form  of  scientific  statement, 
and  to  accomplish  for  social  values  in  general  what  the  physical 
sciences  have  done  for  the  ph5^sical  world.  In  Dewey's  teleological 
pragmatic  logic  the  judgment  is  essentially  instrumental,  the  whole 
of  thinking  is  functional,  and  the  meaning  of  things  is  identical 
with  valid  meaning  (Studies  in  Logical  Theory,  cf.  pp.  48,  82,  128). 
The  real  world  is  not  a  self-existent  world  outside  of  knowledge,  but 
simply  the  totality  of  experience;  and  experience  is  a  complex  of 
strains,  tensions,  checks,  and  attitudes.  The  function  of  logic  is  the 
redintegration  of  this  experience.  "  Thinking  is  adaptation  to  an  end 
through  the  adjustment  of  particular  objective  contents  "  (ihid. 
p.  81).  Logic  here  becomes  a  large  part,  if  not  the  whole,  of  a  meta- 
physics of  experience ;  its  nature  and  function  are  entirely  determined 
by  the  theory  of  reality. 

In  this  brief  and  fragmentary  resume  are  exhibited  certain  charac- 
teristic movements  in  the  development  of  logical  theory,  the  construc- 
tion put  upon  its  subject-matter  and  its  relation  to  other  disciplines. 
The  resume  has  had  in  view  only  the  making  of  the  diversity  of 
opinion  on  these  questions  historically  salient.  There  are  three 
distinct  types  of  logic  noticed  here:    (1)  formal,  whose  concern  is 


RELATIONS   OF  LOGIC   TO   OTHER   DISCIPLINES  307 

merely  with  the  structural  aspect  of  inferential  thought,  and  its 
validity  in  terms  of  internal  congruity;  (2)  metaphysical  logic  whose 
concern  is  with  the  functional  aspect  of  thought,  its  validity  in 
terms  of  objective  reference,  and  its  relation  to  reality;  (3)  epi- 
stemological  and  methodological  logic,  whose  concern  is  with  the 
genesis,  nature,  and  laws  of  logical  thinking  as  forms  of  scientific 
knowledge,  and  with  their  technological  application  to  the  sciences 
as  methodology.  I  am  not  at  present  concerned  with  a  criticism 
of  these  various  viewpoints,  excepting  in  so  far  as  they  affect  the 
problem  of  the  interrelationship  of  logic  and  the  allied  disciplines. 

For  my  present  purpose  I  reject  the  extreme  metaphysical  and 
formal  positions,  and  assume  that  logic  is  a  discipline  whose  busi- 
ness is  to  describe  and  systematize  the  formal  processes  of  inferential 
thought  and  to  apply  them  as  practical  principles  to  the  body  of 
real  knowledge. 

I  wish  now  to  take  up  seriatim  the  several  questions  touching 
the  various  relations  of  logic  enumerated  above,  and  first  of  all  the 
question  of  the  relation  of  logic  as  science  to  logic  as  art. 

I.  Logic  as  science  and  logic  as  art. 

It  seems  true  that  the  founder  of  logic,  Aristotle,  regarded  logic 
not  as  a  science,  but  rather  as  propaedeutic  to  science,  and  not  as  an 
end  in  itself,  but  rather  technically  and  heuristically  as  an  instrument. 
In  other  words,  logic  was  conceived  by  him  rather  in  its  application 
or  as  an  art,  than  as  a  science,  and  so  it  continued  to  be  regarded 
until  the  close  of  the  Middle  Ages,  being  characterized  indeed  as  the 
ars  artium;  for  even  the  logica  docens  of  the  Scholastics  was  merely 
the  formulation  of  that  body  of  precepts  which  are  of  practical  serv- 
ice in  the  syllogistic  arrangement  of  premises,  and  the  Port  Royal 
Logic  aims  to  furnish  I'art  de  penser.  This  technical  aspect  of  the 
science  has  clung  to  it  down  to  the  present  day,  and  is  no  doubt 
a  legitimate  description  of  a  part  of  its  function.  But  no  one  would 
now  say  that  logic  is  an  art;  rather  it  is  a  body  of  theory  which 
may  be  technically  applied.  Mill,  in  his  examination  of  Sir  William 
Hamilton's  Philosophy  (p.  391),  says  of  logic  that  it  "is  the  art  of 
thinking,  which  means  of  correct  thinking,  and  the  science  of  the 
conditions  of  correct  thinking,"  and  indeed,  he  goes  so  far  as  to  say 
(System  of  Logic,  Introd.  §  7) :  "  The  extension  of  logic  as  a  science 
is  determined  by  its  necessities  as  an  art."  Strictly  speaking,  logic 
as  a  science  is  purely  theoretical,  for  the  function  of  science  as  such 
is  merely  to  know.  It  is  an  organized  system  of  knowledge,  namely, 
an  organized  system  of  the  principles  and  conditions  of  correct 
thinking.  But  because  correct  thinking  is  an  art,  it  does  not  follow 
that  a  knowledge  of  the  methods  and  conditions  of  correct  thinking 


308  LOGIC 

is  art,  which  would  be  a  glaring  case  of  /Aera/iJao-ts  ets  dXXo  yei/os.  The 
art-bearings  of  the  science  are  given  in  the  normative  character  of  its 
subject-matter.  As  a  science  logic  is  descriptive  and  explanatory,  that 
is,  it  describes  and  formulates  the  norms  of  valid  thought,  although 
as  science  it  is  not  normative,  save  in  the  sense  that  the  principles 
formulated  in  it  may  be  normatively  or  regulatively  applied,  in 
which  case  they  become  precepts.  What  is  principle  in  science 
becomes  precept  in  application,  and  it  is  only  when  technically 
applied  that  principles  assume  a  mandatory  character.  Validity  is  not 
created  by  logic.  Logic  merely  investigates  and  states  the  conditions 
and  criteria  of  validity,  being  in  this  reference  a  science  of  evidence. 
In  the  very  fact,  however,  that  logic  is  normative  in  the  sense  of 
describing  and  explaining  the  norms  of  correct  thinking,  its  practical 
or  applied  character  is  given.  Its  principles  as  known  are  science; 
its  principles  as  applied  are  art.  There  is,  therefore,  no  reason  to 
sunder  these  two  things  or  to  call  logic  an  art  merely  or  a  science 
merely ;  for  it  is  both  when  regarded  from  different  viewpoints, 
although  one  must  insist  on  the  fact  that  the  rules  for  practical 
guidance  are,  so  far  as  the  science  is  concerned,  quite  ah  extra.  Logic, 
ethics,  and  aesthetics  are  all  commonly  (and  rightly)  called  norm- 
ative disciplines:  they  are  all  concerned  with  values  and  standards; 
logic  with  validity  and  evidence,  or  values  for  cognition;  ethics 
with  motives  and  moral  quality  in  conduct,  or  values  for  volition; 
aesthetics  with  the  standards  of  beauty,  or  values  for  appreciation 
and  feeling.  Yet  none  of  them  is  or  can  be  merely  normative,  or 
indeed  as  science  normative  at  all;  if  that  were  so,  they  would  not 
be  bodies  of  organized  knowledge,  but  bodies  of  rules.  They  might 
be  well-arranged  codes  of  legislation  on  conduct,  fine  art,  and  evi- 
dence, but  not  sciences.  Strictly  regarded,  it  is  the  descriptive  and 
explanatory  aspect  of  logic  that  constitutes  its  scientific  character, 
while  it  is  the  specific  normative  aspect  that  constitutes  its  logical 
character.  Values,  whether  ethical  or  logical,  without  an  examina- 
tion and  formulation  of  their  ground,  relations,  origin,  and  intercon- 
nection, would  be  merely  rules  of  thumb,  popular  phrases,  or  pastoral 
precepts.  The  actual  methodology  of  the  sciences  or  applied  logic 
is  logic  as  art. 

II.  Relation  of  logic  to  psychology. 

The  differentiation  of  logic  and  psychology  in  such  way  as  to  be 
of  practical  value  in  the  discussion  of  the  disciplines  has  always  been 
a  difficult  matter.  John  Stuart  Mill  was  disposed  to  merge  logic  in 
psychology,  and  Hobhouse,  his  latest  notable  apologete,  draws  no 
fixed  distinction  between  psychology  and  logic,  merely  saying  that 
they  have  different  centres  of  interest,  and  that  their  provinces 


RELATIONS   OF   LOGIC  TO   OTHER   DISCIPLINES    309 

overlap.  Lipps,  in  his  Grundziige  der  Logik  (p.  2),  goes  the  length 
of  saying  that  "Logic  is  a  psychological  discipline,  as  certainly  as 
knowledge  occurs  only  in  the  Psyche,  and  thought,  which  is  developed 
in  knowledge,  is  a  psychical  event."  Now,  if  we  were  to  take  such 
extreme  ground  as  this,  then  ethics,  aesthetics,  and  pure  mathe- 
matics would  become  at  once  branches  of  psychology  and  not  coor- 
dinate disciplines  with  it,  for  volitions,  the  feelings  of  appreciation, 
and  the  reasoning  of  pure  mathematics  are  psychical  events.  Such 
a  theory  plainly  carries  us  too  far  and  would  involve  us  in  confusion. 
That  the  demarcation  between  the  two  disciplines  is  not  a  chasmic 
cleavage,  but  a  line,  and  that,  too,  an  historically  shifting  line,  is 
apparent  from  the  foregoing  historical  resume. 

The  four  main  phases  of  logical  theory  include:  (1)  the  concept 
(although  some  logicians  begin  with  the  judgment  as  temporally 
prior  in  the  evolution  of  language),  (2)  judgment,  (3)  inference,  (4)  the 
methodology  of  the  sciences.  The  entire  concern  of  logic  is,  indeed, 
with  psychical  processes,  but  with  psychical  processes  regarded  from 
a  specific  standpoint,  a  standpoint  different  from  that  of  psychology. 
In  the  first  place  psychology  in  a  certain  sense  is  much  wider  than 
logic,  being  concerned  with  the  whole  of  psychosis  as  such,  including 
the  feelings  and  will  and  the  entire  structure  of  cognition,  whereas 
logic  is  concerned  with  the  particular  cognitive  processes  enumer- 
ated above  (concept,  judgment,  inference),  and  that,  too,  merely 
from  the  point  of  view  of  validity  and  the  grounds  of  validity.  In 
another  sense  psychology  is  narrower  than  logic,  being  concerned 
purely  with  the  description  and  explanation  of  a  particular  field  of 
phenomena,  whereas  logic  is  concerned  with  the  procedure  of  all  the 
sciences  and  is  practically  related  to  them  as  their  formulated 
method.  The  compass  and  aims  of  the  two  disciplines  are  different; 
for  while  psychology  is  in  different  references  both  wider  and  nar- 
rower than  logic,  it  is  also  different  in  the  problems  it  sets  itself, 
its  aim  being  to  describe  and  explain  the  phenomena  of  mind  in  the 
spirit  of  empirical  science,  whereas  the  aim  of  logic  is  only  to  explain 
and  establish  the  laws  of  evidence  and  standards  of  validity.  Logic 
is,  therefore,  selective  and  particular  in  the  treatment  of  mental 
phenomena,  whereas  psychology  is.  universal,  that  is,  it  covers 
the  entire  range  of  mental  processes  as  a  phenomenalistic  science; 
logic  dealing  with  definite  elements  as  a  normative  science.  By  this 
it  is  not  meant  that  the  territory  of  judgment  and  inference  should 
be  delivered  from  the  psychologist  into  the  care  of  the  logician; 
through  such  a  division  of  labor  both  disciplines  would  suffer.  The 
two  disciplines  handle  to  some  extent  the  same  subjects,  so  far  as 
names  are  concerned;  but  the  essence  of  the  logical  problem  is  not 
touched  by  psychology,  and  should  not  be  mixed  up  with  it,  to  the 
confusion  and  detriment  of  both  disciplines.   The  field  of  psychology. 


310  LOGIC 

as  we  have  said,  is  the  whole  of  psychical  phenomena;  the  aim  of 
individual  psychology  in  the  investigation  of  its  field  is:  (1)  to  give 
a  genetic  account  of  cognition,  feeling,  and  will,  or  whatever  be  the 
elements  into  which  consciousness  is  analyzed;  (2)  to  explain  their 
interconnections  causally;  (3)  as  ^a  chemistry  of  mental  life  to 
analyze  its  complexes  into  their  simplest  elements;  (4)  to  explain  the 
totality  structurally  (or  functionally)  out  of  the  elements;  (5)  to 
carry  on  its  investigation  and  set  forth  its  results  as  a  purely  empir- 
ical science;  (6)  psychology  makes  no  attempt  to  evaluate  the 
processes  of  mind  either  in  terms  of  false  and  true,  or  good  and  bad. 
From  this  description  of  the  field  and  function  of  psychology,  based 
on  the  expressions  of  its  modern  exponents,  it  will  be  found  impossible 
to  shelter  logic  under  it  as  a  subordinate  discipline.  If  one  were  to 
enlarge  the  scope  of  psychology  to  mean  rational  psychology,  in  the 
sense  which  Professor  Howison  advocates  {Psychological  Review, 
vol.  Ill,  p.  652),  such  a  subordination  might.be  possible,  but  it  would 
entail  the  loss  of  all  that  the  new  psychology  has  gained  by  the 
sharper  delimitation  of  its  sphere  and  problems,  and  would  carry  us 
back  to  the  position  of  Mill,  who  appears  to  identify  psychology 
with  philosophy  at  large  and  with  metaphysics. 

In  contradistinction  to  the  aims  of  psychology  as  described  in 
the  foregoing,  the  sphere  and  problems  of  logic  may  be  summarily 
characterized  as  follows:  (1)  All  concepts  and  judgments  are  psycho- 
logical complexes  and  processes  and  may  be  genetically  and  struc- 
turally described ;  that  is  the  business  of  psychology.  They  also  have 
a  meaning  value,  or  objective  reference,  that  is,  they  may  be  correct 
or  incorrect,  congruous  or  incongruous  with  reality.  The  meaning, 
aspect  of  thought,  or  its  content  as  truth  is  the  business  of  logic. 
This  subject-matter  is  got  by  regarding  a  single  aspect  in  the 
total  psychological  complex.  (2)  Its  aim  is  not  to  describe  factual 
thought  or  the  whole  of  thought,  or  the  natural  processes  of  thought, 
but  only  certain  ideals  of  thinking,  namely,  the  norms  of  correct 
thinking.  Its  object  is  not  a  datum,  but  an  ideal.  (3)  While  psycho- 
logy is  concerned  with  the  natural  history  of  reasoning,  logic  is 
concerned  with  the  warrants  of  inferential  reasoning.  In  the  term- 
inology of  Hamilton  it  is  the  nomology  of  discursive  thought.  To 
use  an  often  employed  analogy,  psychology  is  the  physics  of  thought, 
logic  an  ethics  of  thought.  (4)  Logic  implies  an  epistemology  or 
theory  of  cognition  in  so  far  as  epistemology  discusses  the  concept 
and  judgment  and  their  relations  to  the  real  world,  and  here  is  to  be 
found  its  closest  connection  with  psychology.  A  purely  formal  logic, 
which  is  concerned  merely  with  the  internal  order  of  knowledge  and 
does  not  undertake  to  show  how  the  laws  of  thought  originate,  why 
they  hold  good  as  the  measures  of  evidence,  or  in  what  way  they  are 
applicable  to  concrete  reality,  would  be  as  barren  as  scholasticism. 


RELATIONS   OF   LOGIC   TO  OTHER  DISCIPLINES    311 

(5)  While  logic  thus  goes  back  to  epistemology  for  its  bases  and  for 
the  theoretical  determination  of  the  interrelation  of  knowledge  and 
truth,  it  goes  forward  in  its  application  to  the  practical  service  of  the 
sciences  as  their  methodology,  A  part  of  its  subject-matter  is  therefore 
the  actual  procedure  of  the  sciences,  which  it  attempts  to  organize 
into  systematic  statements  as  principles  and  formulae.  This  body  of 
rules  given  implicitly  or  explicitly  in  the  workings  and  structure  of 
the  special  sciences,  consisting  in  classification,  analysis,  experiment, 
induction,  deduction,  nomenclature,  etc.,  logic  regards  as  a  concrete 
deposit  of  inferential  experience.  It  abstracts  these  principles  from 
the  content  and  method  of  the  sciences,  describes  and  explains  them, 
erects  them  into  a  systematic  methodology,  and  so  creates  the 
practical  branch  of  real  logic.  Formal  logic,  therefore,  according  to 
the  foregoing  account,  would  embrace  the  questions  of  the  internal 
congruity  and  self-consistency  of  thought  and  the  schematic  arrange- 
ment of  judgments  to  insure  formally  valid  conclusions;  real  logic 
would  embrace  the  epistemological  questions  of  how  knowledge  is 
related  to  reality,  and  how  it  is  built  up  out  of  experience,  on  the 
one  hand,  and  the  methodological  procedure  of  science,  on  the  other. 
The  importance  of  mathematical  logic  seems  to  be  mainly  in  the 
facilitation  of  logical  expression  through  symbols.  It  is  rather  with 
the  machinery  of  the  science  than  with  its  content  and  real  problem 
that  the  logical  algorithm  or  calculus  is  concerned.  In  these  con- 
densed paragraphs  sufficient  has  been  said,  I  think,  to  show  that  logic 
and  psychology  should  be  regarded  as  coordinate  disciplines;  for  their 
aims  and  subject-matter  differ  too  widely  to  subordinate  the  former 
under  the  latter  mthout  confusion  to  both. 

I  wish  now  to  add  a  brief  note  on  the  relation  of  logic  to  another 
discipline. 

III.  Relation  of  logic  to  metaphysics. 

As  currently  expounded,  logic  either  abuts  immediately  on  the 
territory  of  metaphysics  at  certain  points  or  is  entirely  absorbed  in  it 
as  an  integral  part  of  the  metaphysical  subject-matter.  I  regard  the 
former  view  as  not  only  the  more  tenable  theoretically,  but  as 
practically  advantageous  for  working  purposes,  and  necessary  for 
an  intelligible  classification  of  the  philosophical  disciplines.  The 
business  of  metaphysics,  as  I  understand  it,  is  with  the  nature  of 
reality;  logic  is  concerned  with  the  nature  of  validity,  or  with  the 
relations  of  the  elements  of  thought  within  themselves  (self-consist- 
ency) and  with  the  relations  of  thought  to  its  object  (real  truth),  but 
not  with  the  nature  of  the  objective  world  or  reality  as  such.  Further, 
metaphysics  is  concerned  with  the  unification  of  the  totality  of 
knowledge  in  the  form  of  a  scientific  cosmology;   logic  is  concerned 


312  LOGIC 

merely  with  the  inferential  and  methodological  processes  whereby 
this  result  is  reached.  The  former  is  a  science  of  content;  the  latter  is 
a  science  of  procedure  and  relations.  Now,  inasmuch  as  procedure 
and  relations  apply  to  some  reality  and  differ  with  different  forms  of 
reality,  logic  necessitates  in  its  implications  a  theory  of  being,  but 
such  implications  are  in  no  wise  to  be  identified  with  its  subject- 
matter  or  with  its  own  proper  problems.  Their  consideration  falls 
within  the  sphere  of  metaphysics  or  a  broadly  conceived  epistemo- 
logy,  whose  business  it  is  to  solve  the  ultimate  questions  of  subject 
and  object,  thought  and  thing,  mind  and  matter,  that  are  implied 
and  pointed  to  rather  than  formulated  by  logic.  Inasmuch  as  the 
logical  judgment  says  something  about  something,  the  scientific 
impulse  drives  us  to  investigate  what  the  latter  something  ultimately 
is;  but  this  is  not  necessary  for  logic,  nor  is  it  one  of  logic's  legitimate 
problems,  any  more  than  it  is  the  proper  business  of  the  physicist  to 
investigate  the  mental  implications  of  his  scientific  judgments  and 
hypotheses  or  the  ultimate  nature  of  the  theorizing  and  perceiving 
mind,  or  of  causality  to  his  world  of  matter  and  motion,  although  a 
general  scientific  interest  may  drive  him  to  seek  a  solution  of  these 
ultimate  metaphysical  problems.  Scientifically  the  end  of  logic  and 
of  every  discipline  is  in  itself;  it  is  a  territorial  unity,  and  its  govern- 
ment is  administered  with  a  unitary  aim.  Logic  is  purely  a  science 
of  evidential  values,  not  a  science  of  content  (in  the  meaning  of 
particular  reality,  as  in  the  special  sciences,  or  of  ultimate  reality, 
as  in  metaphysics) ;  its  sole  aim  and  purpose,  as  I  conceive  it,  is  to 
formulate  the  laws  and  grounds  of  evidence,  the  principles  of  method, 
and  the  conditions  and  forms  of  inferential  thinking.  When  it  has 
done  this,  it  has,  as  a  single  science,  done  its  whole  work.  When  one 
looks  at  the  present  tendencies  of  logical  theory,  one  is  inclined  to 
believe  that  the  discipline  is  in  danger  of  becoming  an  "  Allerleiwis- 
senschaft/'  whose  vast  undefined  territory  is  the  land  of  "  Weiss- 
nichtwo."  The  strict  delimitation  of  the  field  and  problems  of  science 
is  demanded  in  the  interest  of  a  serviceable  division  of  scientific  labor 
and  in  the  interest  of  an  intelligible  classification  of  the  accumulated 
products  of  research. 


THE   FIELD   OF   LOGIC 

BY    FREDERICK   J.    E.    WOODBRIDGE 

[Frederick  J.  E.  Woodbridge,  Johnsonian  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Columbia 
University,  New  York,  N.  Y.,  since  1902.  b.  Windsor,  Ontario,  Canada, 
March  26,  1867.  A.B.  Amherst  College,  1889;  Union  Theological  Seminary, 
1892;  A.M.  1898,  LL.D.  1903,  Amherst  College.  Post-grad.  Berlin  Univers- 
ity. Instructor  in  Philosophy,  University  of  Minnesota,  1894-95;  Professor 
of  Philosophy  and  head  of  department,  1895-1902.  Member  of  American 
Association  for  the  Advancement  of  Science,  American  Philosophical  Associ- 
ation, American  Pyschological  Association.  Editor  of  the  Journal  of  Philo- 
sophy, Psychology  and  Scientific  Methods.] 

Current  tendencies  in  logical  theory  make  a  determination  of  the 
field  of  logic  fundamental  to  any  statement  of  the  general  problems 
of  the  science.  In  view  of  this  fact,  I  propose  in  this  paper  to  attempt 
such  a  determination  by  a  general  discussion  of  the  relation  of  logic 
to  mathematics,  psychology,  and  biology,  especially  noting  in  con- 
nection with  biology  the  tendency  known  as  pragmatism.  In  con- 
clusion, I  shall  indicate  what  the  resulting  general  problems  appear 
to  be. 

I 

There  may  appear,  at  first,  little  to  distinguish  mathematics  in  its 
most  abstract,  formal,  and  symbolic  type  from  logic.  Indeed,  math- 
ematics as  the  universal  method  of  all  knowledge  has  been  the  ideal 
of  many  philosophers,  and  its  right  to  be  such  has  been  claimed  of 
late  with  renewed  force.  The  recent  notable  advances  in  the  science 
have  done  much  to  make  this  claim  plausible.  A  logician,  a  non- 
mathematical  one,  might  be  tempted  to  say  that,  in  so  far  as  mathe- 
matics is  the  method  of  thought  in  general,  it  has  ceased  to  be 
mathematics;  but,  I  suppose,  one  ought  not  to  quarrel  too  much 
with  a  definition,  but  should  let  mathematics  mean  knowledge 
simply,  if  the  mathematicians  wish  it.  I  shall  not,  therefore,  enter 
the  controversy  regarding  the  proper  limits  of  mathematical  inquiry. 
I  wish  to  note,  however,  a  tendency  in  the  identification  of  logic  and 
mathematics  which  seems  to  me  to  be  inconsistent  with  the  real 
significance  of  knowledge.  I  refer  to  the  exaltation  of  the  freedom 
of  thought  in  the  construction  of  conceptions,  definitions,  and  hypo- 
theses. 

The  assertion  that  mathematics  is  a  "pure"  science  is  often  taken 
to  mean  that  it  is  in  no  way  dependent  on  experience  in  the  construc- 
tion of  its  basal  concepts.  The  space  with  which  geometry  deals 
may  be  Euclidean  or  not,  as  we  please;  it  may  be  the  real  space  of 


314  LOGIC 

experience  or  not;  the  properties  of  it  and  the  conclusions  reached 
about  it  may  hold  in  the  real  world  or  they  may  not;  for  the  mind  is 
free  to  construct  its  conception  and  definition  of  space  in  accordance 
with  its  own  aims.  Whether  geometry  is  to  be  ultimately  a  science 
of  this  type  must  be  left,  I  suppose,  for  the  mathematicians  to  decide. 
A  logician  may  suggest,  however,  that  the  propriety  of  calling  all 
these  conceptions  ''space"  is  not  as  clear  as  it  ought  to  be.  Still 
further,  there  seems  to  underlie  all  arbitrary  spaces,  as  their  founda- 
tion, a  good  deal  of  the  solid  material  of  empirical  knowledge,  gained 
by  human  beings  through  contact  with  an  environing  world,  the 
environing  character  of  which  seems  to  be  quite  independent  of 
the  freedom  of  their  thought.  However  that  may  be,  it  is  evident, 
I  think,  that  the  generalization  of  the  principle  involved  in  this  idea 
of  the  freedom  of  thought  in  framing  its  conception  of  space,  would, 
if  extended  to  logic,  give  us  a  science  of  knowledge  which  would 
have  no  necessary  relation  to  the  real  things  of  experience,  although 
these  are  the  things  with  which  all  concrete  knowledge  is  most 
evidently  concerned.  It  would  inform  us  about  the  conclusions 
which  necessarily  follow  from  accepted  conceptions,  but  it  could 
not  inform  us  in  any  way  about  the  real  truth  of  these  conclusions. 
It  would,  thus,  always  leave  a  gap  between  our  knowledge  and  its 
objects  which  logic  itself  would  be  quite  impotent  to  close.  Truth 
would  thus  become  an  entirely  extra-logical  matter.  So  far  as  the 
science  of  knowledge  is  concerned,  it  would  be  an  accident  if  knowledge 
fitted  the  world  to  which  it  refers.  Such  a  conception  of  the  science 
of  knowledge  is  not  the  property  of  a  few  mathematicians  exclusively, 
although  they  have,  perhaps,  done  more  than  others  to  give  it  its 
present  revived  vitality.  It  is  the  classic  doctrine  that  logic  is  the 
science  of  thought  as  thought,  meaning  thereby  thought  in  inde- 
pendence of  any  specific  object  whatever. 

In  regard  to  this  doctrine,  I  would  not  even  admit  that  such  a 
science  of  knowledge  is  possible.  You  cannot,  by  a  process  of  general- 
ization or  free  construction,  rid  thought  of  connection  with  objects; 
and  there  is  no  such  thing  as  a  general  content  or  as  content-in- 
general.  Generalization  simply  reduces  the  richness  of  content  and, 
consequently,  of  implication.  It  deals  with  concrete  subject-matter 
as  much  and  as  directly  as  if  the  content  were  individual  and  ^p'^'cial- 
ized.  "Things  equal  to  the  same  thing  are  equal  to  each  other,"  is  a 
truth,  not  about  thought,  but  about  things.  The  conclusions  about 
a  fourth  dimension  follow,  not  from  the  fact  that  we  have  thought 
of  one,  but  from  the  conception  about  it  which  we  have  framed. 
Neither  generalization  nor  free  construction  can  reveal  the  operations 
of  thought  in  transcendental  independence. 

It  may  be  urged,  however,  that  nothing  of  this  sort  was  ever 
claimed.    The  bondage  of  thought  to  content  must  be  admitted,  but 


THE  FIELD   OF   LOGIC  315 

generalization  and  free  construction,  just  because  they  give  us  the 
power  to  vary  conditions  as  we  please,  give  us  thinking  in  a  relative 
independence  of  content,  and  thus  show  us  how  thought  operates 
irrespective  of,  although  not  independent  of,  its  content.  The  bino- 
mial theorem  operates  irrespective  of  the  values  substituted  for  its 
symbols.  But  I  can  find  no  gain  in  this  restatement  of  the  position. 
It  is  true,  in  a  sense,  that  we  may  determine  the  way  thought  operates 
irrespective  of  any  specific  content  by  the  processes  of  generalization 
and  free  construction;  but  it  is  important  to  know  in  what  sense. 
Can  we  claim  that  such  irrespective  operation  means  that  we  have 
discovered  certain  logical  constants,  which  now  stand  out  as  the 
distinctive  tools  of  thought?  Or  does  it  rather  mean  that  this  process 
of  varying  the  content  of  thought  as  we  please  reveals  certain  real 
constants,  certain  ultimate  characters  of  reality,  which  no  amount  of 
generalization  or  free  construction  can  possibly  alter?  The  second 
alternative  seems  to  me  to  be  the  correct  one.  Whether  it  is  or  not 
may  be  left  here  undecided.  What  I  wish  to  emphasize  is  the  fact 
that  the  decision  is  one  of  the  things  of  vital  interest  for  logic,  and 
properly  belongs  in  that  science.  Clearly,  we  can  never  know  the 
significance  of  ultimate  constants  for  our  thinking  until  we  know 
what  their  real  character  is.  To  determine  that  character  we  must 
most  certainly  pass  out  of  the  realm  of  generalization  and  free  con- 
struction; logic  must  become  other  than  simply  mathematical  or 
symbolic. 

There  is  another  sense  in  which  the  determination  of  the  operations 
of  thought  irrespective  of  its  specific  content  is  interpreted  in  con- 
nection wath  the  exaltation  of  generalization  and  free  construction. 
Knowledge,  it  is  said,  is  solely  a  matter  of  implication,  and  logic, 
therefore,  is  the  science  of  implication  simply.  If  this  is  so,  it  would 
appear  possible  to  develop  the  whole  doctrine  of  implication  by  the 
use  of  symbols,  and  thus  free  the  doctrine  from  dependence  on  the 
question  as  to  how  far  these  symbols  are  themselves  related  to  the 
real  things  of  the  world.  If,  for  instance,  a  implies  h,  then,  if  a  is 
true,  6  is  true,  and  this  quite  irrespective  of  the  real  truth  of  a  or  h. 
It  is  to  be  urged,  however,  in  opposition  to  this  view,  that  knowledge 
is  concerned  ultimately  only  with  the  real  truth  of  a  and  h,  and 
that  the  implication  is  of  no  significance  whatever  apart  from  this 
truth.  There  is  no  virtue  in  the  mere  implication.  Still  further,  the 
supposition  that  there  can  be  a  doctrine  of  implication,  simply, 
seems  to  be  based  on  a  misconception.  For  even  so-called  formal 
implication  gets  its  significance  only  on  the  supposed  truth  of  the 
terms  with  which  it  deals.  We  suppose  that  a  does  imply  6,  and  that 
a  is  true.  In  other  words,  we  can  state  this  law  of  implication  only 
as  we  first  have  valid  instances  of  it  given  in  specific,  concrete  cases. 
The  law  is  a  generalization  and  nothing  more.  The  formal  statement 


316  LOGIC 

gives  only  an  apparent  freedom  from  experience.  Moreover,  there  is 
no  reason  for  saying  that  a  implies  h  unless  it  does  so  either  really  or 
by  supposition.  If  a  really  implies  b,  then  the  implication  is  clearly 
not  a  matter  of  thinking  it;  and  to  suppose  the  implication  is  to  feign 
a  reality,  the  implications  of  which  are  equally  free  from  the  processes 
by  which  they  are  thought.  Ultimately,  therefore,  logic  must  take 
account  of  real  implications.  We  cannot  avoid  this  through  the  use 
of  a  symbolism  which  virtually  implies  them.  Implication  can  have 
a  logical  character  only  because  it  has  first  a  metaphysical  one. 

The  supposition  underlying  the  conception  of  logic  I  have  been 
examining  is,  itself,  open  to  doubt  and  seriously  questioned.  That 
supposition  was  the  so-called  freedom  of  thought.  The  argument 
has  already  shown  that  there  is  certainly  a  very  definite  limit  to  this 
freedom,  even  when  logic  is  conceived  in  a  very  abstract  and  formal 
way.  The  processes  of  knowledge  are  bound  up  with  their- contents, 
and  have  their  character  largely  determined  thereby.  When,  more- 
over, we  view  knowledge  in  its  genesis,  when  we  take  into  considera- 
tion the  contributions  which  psychology  and  biology  have  made  to 
our  general  view  of  what  knowledge  is,  we  seem  forced  to  conclude 
that  the  conceptions  which  we  frame  are  very  far  from  being  our  own 
free  creations.  They  have,  on  the  contrary,  been  laboriously  worked 
out  through  the  same  processes  of  successful  adaptation  which  have 
resulted  in  other  products.  Knowledge  has  grown  up  in  connection 
with  the  unfolding  processes  of  reality,  and  has,  by  no  means,  freely 
played  over  its  surface.  That  is  why  even  the  most  abstract  of  all 
mathematics  is  yet  grounded  in  the  evolution  of  human  experience. 

In  the  remaining  parts  of  this  paper,  I  shall  discuss  further  the 
claims  of  psychology  and  biology.  The  conclusion  I  would  draw 
here  is  that  the  field  of  logic  cannot  be  restricted  to  a  realm  where 
the  operations  of  thought  are  supposed  to  move  freely,  independent 
or  irrespective  of  their  contents  and  the  objects  of  a  real  world; 
and  that  mathematics,  instead  of  giving  us  any  support  for  the 
supposition  that  it  can,  carries  us,  by  the  processes  of  symbolization 
and  formal  implication,  to  recognize  that  logic  must  ultimately  find 
its  field  where  implications  are  real,  independent  of  the  processes 
by  which  they  are  thought,  and  irrespective  of  the  conceptions  we 
choose  to  frame. 

II 

The  processes  involved  in  the  acquisition  and  systematization  of 
knowledge  may,  undoubtedly,  be  regarded  as  mental  processes  and 
fall  thus  within  the  province  of  psychology.  It  may  be  claimed, 
therefore,  that  every  logical  process  is  also  a  ps3^chological  one.  The 
important  question  is,  however,  is  it  nothing  more?  Do  its  logical 
and  psychological  characters  simply  coincide?    Or,  to  put  the  ques- 


THE  FIELD   OF   LOGIC  317 

tion  in  still  another  form,  as  a  psychological  process  simply,  does 
it  also  serve  as  a  logical  one?  .The  answers  to  these  questions  can  be 
determined  only  by  first  noting  what  psychology  can  say  about  it 
as  a  mental  process. 

In  the  first  place,  psychology  can  analyze  it,  and  so  determine 
its  elements  and  their  connections.  It  can  thus  distinguish  it  from  all 
other  mental  processes  by  pointing  out  its  unique  elements  or  their 
unique  and  characteristic  connection.  No  one  will  deny  that  a 
judgment  is  different  from  an  emotion,  or  that  an  act  of  reasoning  is 
different  from  a  volition;  and  no  one  will  claim  that  these  differences 
are  entirely  beyond  the  psychologist's  power  to  ascertain  accurately 
and  precisely.  Still  further,  it  appears  possible  for  him  to  determine 
with  the  same  accuracy  and  precision  the  distinction  in  content  and 
connection  between  processes  which  are  true  and  those  which  are 
false.  For,  as  mental  processes,  it  is  natural  to  suppose  that  they 
contain  distinct  differences  of  character  which  are  ascertainable. 
The  states  of  mind  called  belief,  certainty,  conyiction,  correctness, 
truth,  are  thus,  doubtless,  all  distinguishable  as  mental  states.  It 
may  be  admitted,  therefore,  that  there  can  be  a  thoroughgoing 
psychology  of  logical  processes. 

Yet  it  is  quite  evident  to  me  that  the  characterization  of  a  mental 
process  as  logical  is  not  a  psychological  characterization.  In  fact, 
I  think  it  may  be  claimed  that  the  characterization  of  any  mental 
process  in  a  specific  way,  say  as  an  emotion,  is  extra-psychological. 
Judgments  and  inferences  are,  in  short,  not  judgments  and  inferences 
because  they  admit  of  psychological  analysis  and  explanation,  any 
more  than  space  is  space  because  the  perception  of  it  can  be  worked 
out  by  genetic  psychology.  In  other  words,  knowledge  is  first  know- 
ledge, and  only  later  a  set  of  processes  for  psychological  analysis. 
That  is  why,  as  it  seems  to  me,  all  psychological  logicians,  from  Locke 
to  our  own  day,  have  signally  failed  in  dealing  with  the  problem  of 
knowledge.  The  attempt  to  construct  knowledge  out  of  mental 
states,  the  relations  between  ideas,  and  the  relation  of  ideas  to 
things,  has  been,  as  I  read  the  history,  decidedly  without  profit. 
Confusion  and  divergent  opinion  have  resulted  instead  of  agreement 
and  confidence.  On  precisely  the  same  psychological  foundation, 
we  have  such  divergent  views  of  knowledge  as  idealism,  phenomenal- 
ism, and  agnosticism,  with  many  other  strange  mixtures  of  logic, 
psychology,  and  metaphysics.  The  lesson  of  these  perplexing  theories 
seems  to  be  that  logic,  as  logic,  must  be  divorced  from  psychology. 

It  is  also  of  importance  to  note,  in  this  connection,  that  the  deter- 
mination of  a  process  as  mental  and  as  thus  falling  within  the  domain 
of  psychology  strictly,  has  by  no  means  been  worked  out  to  the 
general  satisfaction  of  psychologists  themselves.  Recent  literature 
abounds  in  elaborate  discussion  of  the  distinction  between  what  is 


318  LOGIC 

a  mental  fact  and  what  not,  with  a  prevailing  tendency  to  draw  the 
remarkable  conclusion  that  all  facts  are  somehow  mental  or  experi- 
enced facts.  The  situation  would  be  worse  for  psychology  than  it  is, 
if  that  vigorous  science  had  not  learned  from  other  sciences  the  valu- 
able knack  of  isolating  concrete  problems  and  attacking  them 
directly,  without  the  burden  of  previous  logical  or  metaphysical 
speculation.  Thus  knowledge,  which  is  the  peculiar  province  of  logic, 
is  increased,  while  we  wait  for  the  acceptable  definition  of  a  mental 
fact.  But  definitions,  be  it  remembered,  are  themselves  logical 
matters.  Indeed,  some  psychologists  have  gone  so  far  as  to  claim 
that  the  distinction  of  a  fact  as  mental  is  a  purely  logical  distinc- 
tion. This  is  significant  as  indicating  that  the  time  has  not  yet  come 
for  the  identification  of  logic  and  psychology. 

In  refreshingly  sharp  contrast  to  the  vagueness  and  uncertainty 
which  beset  the  definition  of  a  mental  fact  are  the  palpable  concrete- 
ness  and  definiteness  of  knowledge  itself.  Every  science,  even  history 
and  philosophy,  are  instances  of  it.  What  constitutes  a  knowledge 
ought  to  be  as  definite  and  precise  a  question  as  could  be  asked. 
That  logic  has  made  no  more  progress  than  it  has  in  the  answer  to  it 
appears  to  be  due  to,  the  fact  that  it  has  not  sufficiently  grasped  the 
significance  of  its  own  simplicity.  Knowledge  has  been  the  important 
business  of  thinking  man,  and  he  ought  to  be  able  to  tell  what  he  does 
in  order  to  know,  as  readily  as  he  tells  what  he  does  in  order  to  build 
a  house.  And  that  is  why  the  Aristotelian  logic  has  held  its  own  so 
long.  In  that  logic,  "  the  master  of  them  that  know"  simply  rehearsed 
the  way  he  had  systematized  his  own  stores  of  knowledge.  Naturally 
we,  so  far  as  we  have  followed  his  methods,  have  had  practically 
nothing  to  add.  In  our  efforts  to  improve  on  him,  we  have  too  often 
left  the  right  way  and  followed  the  impossible  method  inaugurated 
by  Locke.  Had  we  examined  with  greater  persistence  our  own 
methods  of  making  science,  we  should  have  profited  more.  The 
introduction  of  psychology,  instead  of  helping  the  situation,  only 
confuses  it. 

Let  it  be  granted,  however,  in  spite  of  the  vagueness  of  what  is 
meant  by  a  mental  fact,  that  logical  processes  are  also  mental  pro- 
cesses. This  fact  has,  as  I  have  already  suggested,  an  important 
bearing  on  their  genesis,  and  sets  very  definite  limits  to  the  freedom 
of  thought  in  creating.  It  is  not,  however,  as  mental  processes  that 
they  have  the  value  of  knowledge.  A  mental  process  which  is  know- 
ledge purports  to  be  connected  with  something  other  than  itself, 
something  which  may  not  be  a  mental  process  at  all.  This  connection 
should  be  investigated,  but  the  investigation  of  it  belongs,  not  to 
psychology,  but  to  logic. 

I  am  well  aware  that  this  conclusion  runs  counter  to  some  meta- 
physical doctrines,  and  especially  to  idealism  in  all  its  forms,  with  the 


THE  FIELD   OF   LOGIC  319 

epistemologies  based  thereon.  It  is,  of  course,  impossible  here  to 
defend  my  position  by  an  elaborate  analysis  of  these  metaphysical 
systems.  But  I  will  say  this.  I  am  in  entire  agreement  with  idealism 
in  its  claim  that  questions  of  knowledge  and  of  the  nature  of  reality 
cannot  ultimately  be  separated,  because  we  can  know  reality  only 
as  we  know  it.  But  the  general  question  as  to  how  we  know  reality 
can  still  be  raised.  By  this  I  do  not  mean  the  question,  how  is  it 
possible  for  us  to  have  knowledge  at  all,  or  how  it  is  possible  for  reality 
to  be  known  at  all,  but  how,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  we  actually  do  know 
it?  That  we  really  do  know  it,  I  would  most  emphatically  claim. 
Still  further,  I  would  claim  that  what  we  know  about  it  is  determined, 
not  by  the  fact  that  we  can  know  in  general,  but  by  the  way  reality, 
as  distinct  from  our  knowledge,  has  determined.  These  ways  appear 
to  me  to  be  ascertainable,  and  form,  thus,  undoubtedly,  a  section 
of  metaphysics.  But  the  metaphysics  will  naturally  be  realistic  rather 
than  idealistic.  ^     , 

III 

Just  as  logical  processes  may  be  regarded  as,  at  the  same  time, 
psychological  processes,  so  they  may  be  regarded,  with  equal  right, 
as  vital  processes,  coming  thus  under  the  categories  of  evolution. 
The  tendency  so  to  regard  them  is  very  marked  at  the  present  day, 
especially  in  France  and  in  this  country.  In  France,  the  movement 
has  perhaps  received  the  clearer  definition.  In  America  the  union  of 
logic  and  biology  is  complicated  —  and  at  times  even  lost  sight  of  — 
by  emphasis  on  the  idea  of  evolution  generally.  It  is  not  my  intention 
to  trace  the  history  of  this  movement,  but  I  should  like  to  call  atten- 
tion to  its  historic  motive  in  order  to  get  it  in  a  clear  light. 

That  the  theory  of  evolution,  even  Darwinism  itself,  has  radically 
transformed  our  historical,  scientific,  and  philosophical  methods,  is 
quite  evident.  Add  to  this  the  influence  of  the  Hegelian  philosophy, 
with  its  own  doctrine  of  development,  and  one  finds  the  causes  of 
the  rather  striking  unanimity  which  is  discoverable  in  many  ways 
between  Hegelian  idealists,  on  the  one  hand,  and  philosophers  of 
evolution  of  Spencer's  type,  on  the  other.  Although  two  men  would, 
perhaps,  not  appear  more  radically  different  at  first  sight  than  Hegel 
and  Spencer,  I  am  inclined  to  believe  that  we  shall  come  to  recognize 
more  and  more  in  them  an  identity  of  philosophical  conception.  The 
pragmatism  of  the  day  is  a  striking  confirmation  of  this  opinion,  for 
it  is  often  the  expression  of  Hegelian  ideas  in  Darwinian  and  Spencer- 
ian  terminology.  The  claims  of  idealism  and  of  evolutionary  science 
and  philosophy  have  thus  sought  reconciliation.  Logic  has  been, 
naturally,  the  last  of  the  sciences  to  yield  to  evolutionary  and  genetic 
treatment.  It  could  not  escape  long,  especially  when  the  idea  of 
evolution  had  been  so  successful  in  its  handling  of  ethics.  If  morality 


320  LOGIC 

can  be  brought  under  the  categories  of  evolution,  why  not  thinking 
also?  In  answer  to  that  question  we  have  the  theory  that  thinking 
is  an  adaptation,  judgment  is  instrumental.  But  I  would  not  leave 
the  impression  that  this  is  true  of  pragmatism  alone,  or  that  it  has 
been  developed  only  through  pragmatic  tendencies.  It  is  naturally 
the  result  also  of  the  extension  of  biological  philosophy.  In  the 
biological  conception  of  logic,  we  have,  then,  an  interesting  coinci- 
dence in  the  results  of  tendencies  differing  widely  in  their  genesis. 

It  would  be  hazardous  to  deny,  without  any  qualifications,  the 
importance  of  genetic  considerations.  Indeed,  the  fact  that  evolution 
in  the  hands  of  a  thinker  like  Huxley,  for  instance,  should  make  con- 
sciousness and  thinking  apparently  useless  epiphenomena  in  a  devel- 
oping world,  has  seemed  like  a  most  contradictory  evolutionary 
philosophy.  It  was  difficult  to  make  consciousness  a  real  function  in 
development  so  long  as  it  was  regarded  as  only  cognitive  in  character. 
Evolutionary  philosophy,  coupled  with  physics,  had  built  up  a  sort  of 
closed  system  with  which  consciousness  could  not  interfere,  but  which 
it  could  know,  and  know  with  all  the  assurance  of  a  traditional  logic. 
If,  however,  we  were  to  be  consistent  evolutionists,  we  could  not  abide 
by  such  a  remarkable  result.  The  whole  process  of  thinking  must  be 
brought  within  evolution,  so  that  knowledge,  even  the  knowledge  of 
the  evolutionary  hypothesis  itself,  must  appear  as  an  instance  of 
adaptation.  In  order  to  do  this,  however,  consciousness  must  not  be 
conceived  as  only  cognitive.  Judgment,  the  core  of  logical  processes, 
must  be  regarded  as  an  instrument  and  as  a  mode  of  adaptation. 

The  desire  for  completeness  and  consistency  in  an  evolutionary 
philosophy  is  not  the  only  thing  which  makes  the  denial  of  genetic 
considerations  hazardous.  Strictly  biological  considerations  furnish 
reasons  of  equal  weight  for  caution.  For  instance,  one  will  hardly 
deny  that  the  whole  sensory  apparatus  is  a  striking  instance  of 
adaptation.  Our  perceptions  of  the  world  would  thus  appear  to  be 
determined  by  this  adaptation,  to  be  instances  of  adjustment.  They 
might  conceivably  have  been  different,  and  in  the  case  of  many  other 
creatures,  the  perceptions  of  the  world  are  undoubtedly  different. 
All  our  logical  processes,  referring  ultimately  as  they  do  to  our  per- 
ceptions, would  thus  appear  finally  to  depend  on  the  adaptation 
exhibited  in  the  development  of  our  sensory  apparatus.  So-called 
laws  of  thought  would  seem  to  be  but  abstract  statements  or  formu- 
lations of  the  results  of  this  adjustment.  It  would  be  absurd  to  sup- 
pose that  a  man  thinks  in  a  sense  radically  different  from  that  in 
which  he  digests,  or  a  flower  blossoms,  or  that  two  and  two  are  four 
in  a  sense  radically  different  from  that  in  which  a  flower  has  a  given 
number  of  petals.  Thinking,  like  digesting  and  blossoming,  is  an 
effect,  a  product,  possibly  a  structure. 

I  am  not  at  all  interested  in  denying  the  force  of  these  considera- 


THE  FIELD   OF   LOGIC  321 

tions.  They  have,  to  my  mind,  the  greatest  importance,  and  due 
weight  has,  as  yet,  not  been  given  to  them.  To  one  at  all  committed 
to  a  unitary  and  evolutionary  view  of  the  world,  it  must  indeed  seem 
strange  if  thinking  itself  should  not  be  the  result  of  evolution,  or  that, 
in  thinking,  parts  of  the  world  had  not  become  adjusted  in  a  new 
way.  But  while  I  am  ready  to  admit  this,  I  am  by  no  means  ready  to 
admit  some  of  the  conclusions  for  logic  and  metaphysics  which  are 
often  drawn  from  the  admission.  Just  because  thought,  as  a  product 
of  evolution,  is  functional  and  judgment  instrumental,  it  by  no  means 
follows  that  logic  is  but  a  branch  of  biology,  or  that  knowledge  of  the 
world  is  but  a  temporary  adjustment,  which,  as  knowledge,  might 
have  been  radically  different.  In  these  conclusions,  often  drawn  with 
Protagorean  assurance,  two  considerations  of  crucial  importance 
seem  to  be  overlooked,  first,  that  adaptation  is  itself  metaphysical  in 
character,  and  secondly,  that  while  knowledge  may  be  functional  and 
judgment  instrumental,  the  character  of  the  functioning  has  the 
character  of  knowledge,  which  sets  it  off  sharply  from  all  other 
functions. 

It  seems  strange  to  me  that  the  admission  that  knowledge  is  as 
matter  of  adaptation,  and  thus  a  relative  matter,  should,  in  these 
days,  be  regarded  as  in  any  way  destroying  the  claims  of  knowledge 
to  metaphysical  certainty.  Yet,  somehow,  the  opinion  widely  prevails 
that  the  doctrine  of  relativity  necessarily  involves  the  surrender  of 
auA'thing  like  absolute  truth.  ''  All  our  knowledge  is  relative,  and^ 
therefore,  only  partial,  incomplete,  and  but  practically  trustworthy/' 
is  a  statement  repeatedly  made.  The  fact  that,  if  our  development 
had  been  different,  our  knowledge  would  have  been  different,  is 
taken  to  involve  the  conclusion  that  our  knowledge  cannot  possibly 
disclose  the  real  constitution  of  things,  that  it  is  essentially  condi- 
tional, that  it  is  only  a  mental  device  for  getting  results,  that  any 
other  system  of  knowledge  which  would  get  results  equally  well 
would  be  equally  true;  in  short,  that  there  can  be  no  such  thing,  as 
metaphysical  or  epistemological  truth.  These  conclusions  do  indeed 
seem  strange,  and  especially  strange  on  the  basis  of  evolution.  For 
while  the  evolutionary  process  might,  conceivably,  have  been  dif- 
ferent, its  results  are,  in  any  case,  the  results  of  the  process.  They 
are  not  arbitrary.  We  might  have  digested  without  stomachs,  but 
the  fact  that  we  use  stomachs  in  this  important  process  ought  not  to 
free  us  from  metaphysical  respect  for  the  organ.  As  M.  Rey  suggests, 
in  the  Revue  Philosoj)hique  for  June,  1904,  a  creature  without  the 
sense  of  smell  would  have  no  geometry,  but-  that  does  not  make 
geometry  essentially  hypothetical,  a  mere  mental  construction;  for 
we  have  geometry  because  of  the  working  out  of  nature's  laws. 
Indeed,  instead  of  issuing  in  a  relativistic  metaphysics  of  knowledge, 
the  doctrine  of  relativity  should  issue  in  the  recognition  of  the  finality 


322  LOGIC 

of  knowledge  in  every  case  of  ascertainably  complete  adaptation.  In 
other  words,  adaptation  is  itself  metaphysical  in  character.  Adjust- 
ment is  always  adjustment  between  things,  and  yields  only  what  it 
does  yield.  The  things  or  elements  get  into  the  state  which  is  their 
adjustment,  and  this  adjustment  purports  to  be  their  actual  and 
unequivocal  ordering  in  relation  to  one  another.  Different  conditions 
might  have  produced  a  different  ordering,  but,  again,  this  ordering 
would  be  equally  actual  and  unequivocal,  equally  the  one  ordering  to 
issue  from  them.  To  suppose  or  admit  that  the  course  of  events  might 
have  been  and  might  be  different  is  not  at  all  to  suppose  or  admit 
that  it  was  or  is  different;  it  is,  rather,  to  suppose  and  admit  that  we 
have  real  knowledge  of  what  that  course  really  was  and  is.  This  seems 
to  be  very  obvious. 

Yet  the  evolutionist  often  thinks  that  he  is  not  a  metaphysician, 
even  when  he  brings  all  his  conceptions  systematically  under  the 
conception  of  evolution.  This  must  be  due  to  some  temporary  lack  of 
clearness.  If  evolution  is  not  a  metaphysical  doctrine  when  extended 
to  apply  to  all  science,  all  morality,  all  logic,  in  short,  all  things,  then 
it  is  quite  meaningless  for  evolutionists  to  pronounce  a  metaphysical 
sentence  on  logical  processes.  But  if  evolution  is  a  metaphysics,  then 
its  sentence  is  metaphysical,  and  in  every  case  of  adjustment  or 
adaptation  we  have  a  revelation  of  the  nature  of  reality  in  a  definite 
and  unequivocal  form.  This  conclusion  applies  to  logical  processes  as 
well  as  to  others.  The  recognition  that  they  are  vital  processes  can, 
therefore,  have  little  significance  for  these  processes  in  their  distinct- 
ive character  as  logical.  They  are  like  all  other  vital  processes  in 
that  they  are  vital  and  subject  to  evolution.  They  are  unlike  all 
others  in  that  thought  is  unlike  digestion  or  breathing.  To  regard 
logical  processes  as  vital  processes  does  not  in  any  way,  therefore, 
invalidate  them  as  logical  processes  or  make  it  superfluous  to  consider 
their  claim  to  give  us  real  knowledge  of  a  real  world.  Indeed,  it  makes 
such  a  consideration  more  necessary  and  important. 

A  second  consideration  overlooked  by  the  Protagorean  tendencies 
of  the  day  is  that  judgment,  even  if  it  is  instrumental,  purports  to 
give  us  knowledge,  that  is,  it  claims  to  reveal  what  is  independent  of 
the  judging  process.  Perhaps  I  ought  not  to  say  that  this  considera- 
tion is  overlooked,  but  rather  that  it  is  denied  significance.  It  is  even 
denied  to  be  essential  to  judgment.  It  is  claimed  that,  instead  of 
revealing  anything  independent  of  the  judging  process,  judgment  is 
just  the  adjustment  and  no  more.  It  is  a  reorganization  of  experience, 
an  attempt  at  control.  All  this  looks  to  me  like  a  misstatement  of  the 
facts.  Judgment  claims  to  be  no  such  thing.  It  does  not  function  as 
such  a  thing.  When  I  make  any  judgment,  even  the  simplest,  I  may 
make  it  as  the  result  of  tension,  because  of  a  demand  for  reorganiza- 
tion, in  order  to  secure  control  of  experience;    but  the  judgment 


THE  FIELD   OF   LOGIC  323 

means  for  me  something  quite  different.  It  means  decidedly  and 
unequivocally  that  in  reality,  apart  from  the  judging  process,  things 
exist  and  operate  just  as  the  judgment  declares.  If  it  is  claimed  that 
this  meaning  is  illusory,  I  eagerly  desire  to  know  on  what  solid  ground 
its  illusoriness  can  be  established.  AATien  the  conclusion  was  reached 
that  gravitation  varies  directly  as  the  mass  and  inversely  as  the 
square  of  the  distance,  it  was  doubtless  reached  in  an  evolutionary 
and  pragmatic  way;  but  it  claimed  to  disclose  a  fact  which  prevailed 
before  the  conclusion  was  reached,  and  in  spite  of  the  conclusion. 
Knowledge  has  been  born  of  the  travail  of  living,  but  it  has  been 
born  as  knowledge. 

When  the  knowledge  character  of  judgment  is  insisted  on,  it  seems 
almost  incredible  that  any  one  would  think  of  denying  or  overlooking 
it.  Indeed,  current  discussions  are  far  from  clear  on  the  subject. 
Pragmatists  are  constantly  denying  that  they  hold  the  conclusions 
that  their  critics  almost  unanimously  draw.  There  is,  therefore,  a 
good  deal  of  confusion  of  thought  yet  to  be  dispelled.  Yet  there 
seems  to  be  current  a  pronounced  determination  to  banish  the  epi- 
stemological  problem  from  logic.  This  is,  to  my  mind,  suspicious,  even 
when  epistemologj'"  is  defined  in  a  way  which  most  epistemologists 
would  not  approve.  It  is  suspicious  just  because  we  must  always 
ask  eventually  that  most  epistemological  and  metaphysical  question : 
"  Is  knowledge  true?  "  To  answer,  it  is  true  when  it  functions  in  a  way 
to  satisfy  the  needs  which  generated  its  activity,  is,  no  doubt,  correct, 
but  it  is  by  no  means  adequate.  The  same  answer  can  be  made  to 
the  inquiry  after  the  efficiency  of  any  vital  process  whatever,  and  is, 
therefore,  not  distinctive.  We  have  still  to  inquire  into  the  specific 
character  of  the  needs  which  originate  judgments  and  of  the  conse- 
quent satisfaction.  Just  here  is  where  the  uniqueness  of  the  logical 
problem  is  disclosed.  With  conscious  beings,  the  success  of  the  things 
they  do  has  become  increasingly  dependent  on  their  ability  to  discover 
what  takes  place  in  independence  of  the  knowing  process.  That  is  the 
need  which  generates  judgment.  The  satisfaction  is,  of  course,  the 
attainment  of  the  discovery.  Now  to  make  the  judgment  itself  and 
not  the  consequent  action  the  instrumental  factor  seems  to  me  to 
misstate  the  facts  of  the  case.  Nothing  is  clearer  than  that  there 
is  no  necessity  for  knowledge  to  issue  in  adjustment.  And  it  is  clear 
to  me  that  increased  control  of  experience,  while  resulting  from 
knowledge,  does  not  give  to  it  its  character.  Omniscience  could  idly 
view  the  transformations  of  reality  and  yet  remain  omniscient. 
Knowledge  works,  but  it  is  not,  therefore,  knowledge. 

These  considerations  have  peculiar  force  when  applied  to  that 
branch  of  knowledge  which  is  knowledge  itself.  Is  the  biological 
account  of  knowledge  correct?  That  question  we  must  evidently 
ask,  especially  when  we  are  urged  to  accept  the  account.    Can  we, 


324  LOGIC 

to  put  the  question  in  its  most  general  form,  accept  as  an  adequate 
account  of  the  logical  process  a  theory  which  is  bound  up  with  some 
other  specific  department  of  human  knowledge?  It  seems  to  me  that 
we  cannot.  Here  we  must  be  epistemologists  and  metaphysicians, 
or  give  up  the  problem  entirely.  This  by  no  means  involves  the 
attempt  to  conceive  pure  thought  set  over  against  pure  reality  —  the 
kind  of  epistemology  and  metaphysics  justly  ridiculed  by  the  prag- 
matist  —  for  knowledge,  as  already  stated,  is  given  to  us  in  concrete 
instances.  How  knowledge  in  general  is  possible  is,  therefore,  as  use- 
less and  meaningless  a  question  as  how  reality  in  general  is  possible. 
The  knowledge  is  given  as  a  fact  of  life,  and  what  we  have  to  deter- 
mine is  not  its  non-logical  antecedents  or  its  practical  consequences, 
but  its  constitution  as  knowledge  and  its  validity.  It  may  be  admitted 
that  the  question  of  validity  is  settled  pragmatically.  No  knowledge 
is  true  unless  it  yields  results  which  can  be  verified,  unless  it  can  issue 
in  increased  control  of  experience.  But  I  insist  again  that  that  fact 
is  not  sufficient  for  an  account  of  what  knowledge  claims  to  be.  It 
claims  to  issue  in  control  because  it  is  true  in  independence  of  the 
control.  And  it  is  just  this  assurance  that  is  needed  to  distinguish 
knowledge  from  what  is  not  knowledge.  It  is  the  necessity  of  exhibit- 
ing this  assurance  which  makes  it  impossible  to  subordinate  logical 
problems,  and  forces  us  at  last  to  questions  of  epistemology  and 
metaphysics. 

As  I  am  interested  here  primarily  in  determining  the  field  of  logic, 
it  is  somewhat  outside  my  province  to  consider  the  details  of  logical 
theory.  Yet  the  point  just  raised  is  of  so  much,  importance  in  con- 
nection with  the  main  question  that  I  venture  the  following  general 
considerations.  This  is,  perhaps,  the  more  necessary  because  the 
pragmatic  doctrine  finds  in  the  concession  made  regarding  the  test 
of  validity  one  of  its  strongest  defenses. 

Of  course  a  judgment  is  not  true  simply  because  it  is  a  judgment. 
It  may  be  false.  The  only  way  to  settle  its  validity  is  to  discover 
whether  experience  actually  provides  what  the  judgment  promises, 
that  is,  whether  the  conclusions  drawn  from  it  really  enable  us  to 
control  experience.  No  mere  speculation  will  yield  the  desired  result, 
no  matter  with  how  much  formal  validity  the  conclusions  may  be 
drawn.  That  merely  formal  validity  is  not  the  essential  thing,  I 
have  pointed  out  in  discussing  the  relation  of  logic  to  mathematics. 
The  test  of  truth  is  pragmatic.  It  is  apparent,  therefore,  that  the 
formal  validity  does  not  determine  the  actual  validity.  What  is 
this  but  the  statement  that  the  process  of  judgment  is  not  itself  the 
determining  factor  in  its  real  validity?  It  is,  in  short,  only  valid 
judgments  that  can  really  give  us  control  of  experience.  The  impli- 
cations taken  up  in  the  judgment  must,  therefore,  be  real  implica- 
tions which,  as  such,  have  nothing  to  do  with  the  judging  process, 


THE  FIELD   OF   LOGIC  325 

and  which,  most  certainly,  are  not  brought  about  by  it.  And  what 
is  this  but  the  claim  that  judgment  as  such  is  never  instrumental  ? 
In  other  words,  a  judgment  which  effected  its  own  content  would 
only  by  the  merest  accident  function  as  valid  knowledge.  We  have 
valid  knowledge,  then,  only  when  the  implications  of  the  judgment 
are  found  to  be  independent  of  the  judging  process.  We  have  know- 
ledge only  at  the  risk  of  error.  The  pragmatic  test  of  validity,  instead 
of  proving  the  instrumental  character  of  judgment,  would  thus 
appear  to  prove  just  the  reverse. 

Valid  knowledge  has,  therefore,  for  its  content  a  system  of  real, 
not  judged  or  hypothetical  implications.  The  central  problem  of 
logic  which  results  from  this  fact  is  not  how  a  knowledge  of  real 
implications  is  then  possible,  but  what  are  the  ascertainable  types 
of  real  implications.  But,  it  may  be  urged,  we  need  some  criterion  to 
determine  what  a  real  implication  is.  I  venture  to  reply  that  we 
need  none,  if  by  such  is  meant  anything  else  than  the  facts  with 
which  we  are  dealing.  I  need  no  other  criterion  than  the  circle  to 
determine  whether  its  diameters  are  really  equal.  And,  in  general, 
I  need  no  other  criterion  than  the  facts  dealt  with  to  determine 
whether  they  really  imply  what  I  judge  them  to  imply.  Logic  appears 
to  me  to  be  really  as  simple  as  this.  Yet  there  can  be  profound  pro- 
blems involved  in  the  working  out  of  this  simple  procedure.  There  is 
the  problem  already  stated  of  the  most  general  types  of  real  impli- 
cation, or,  in  other  words,  the  time-honored  doctrine  of  categories. 
Whether  there  are  categories  or  basal  types  of  existence  seems  to  me 
to  be  ascertainable.  When  ascertained,  it  is  also  possible  to  discover 
the  types  of  inference  or  implication  which  they  afford.  This  is  by 
no  means  the  whole  of  logic,  but  it  appears  to  me  to  be  its  central 
problem. 

These  considerations  will,  I  hope,  throw  light  on  the  statement 
that  while  knowledge  works,  it  is  not  therefore  knowledge.  It  works 
because  its  content  existed  before  its  discovery  by  the  knowledge 
process,  and  because  its  content  was  not  effected  or  brought  about 
by  that  process.  Judgment  was  the  instrument  of  its  discovery,  not 
the  instrument  which  fashioned  it.  While,  therefore,  willing  to  admit 
that  logical  processes  are  vital  processes,  I  am  not  willing  to  admit 
that  the  problem  of  logic  is  radically  changed  thereby  in  its  formu- 
lation or  solution,  for  the  vital  processes  in  question  have  the  unique 
character  of  knowledge,  the  content  of  which  is  what  it  claims  to  be, 
a  system  of  real  implications  which  existed  prior  to  its  discovery. 

In  the  psychological  and  biological  tendencies  in  logic,  there  is, 
however,  I  think,  a  distinct  gain  for  logical  theory.  The  insistence 
that  logical  processes  are  both  mental  and  vital  has  done  much  to 
take  them  out  of  the  transcendental  aloofness  from  reality  in  which 
they  have  often  been  placed,  especially  since  Kant.     So  long  as 


326  LOGIC 

thought  and  object  were  so  separated  that  they  could  never  be 
brought  together,  and  so  long  as  logical  processes  were  conceived 
wholly  in  terms  of  ideas  set  over  against  objects,  there  was  no  hope 
of  escape  from  the  realm  of  pure  hypothesis  and  conjecture.  Locke's 
axiom  that  "the  mind,  in  all  its  thoughts  and  reasonings,  hath  no 
other  immediate  object  but  its  own  ideas,"  an  axiom  which  Kant 
did  so  much  to  sanctify,  and  which  has  been  the  basal  principle  of 
the  greater  part  of  modern  logic  and  metaphysics,  is  most  certainly 
subversive  of  logical  theory.  The  transition  from  ideas  to  anything 
else  is  rendered  impossible  by  it.  Now  it  is  just  this  axiom  which  the 
biological  tendencies  in  logic  have  done  so  much  to  destroy.  They 
have  insisted,  with  the  greatest  right,  that  logical  processes  are  not 
set  over  against  their  content  as  idea  against  object,  as  appearance 
against  reality,  but  are  processes  of  reality  itself.  Just  as  reality 
can  and  does  function  in  a  physical  or  a  physiological  way,  so  also 
it  functions  in  a  logical  way.  The  state  we  call  knowledge  becomes, 
thus,  as  much  a  part  of  the  system  of  things  as  the  state  we  call 
chemical  combination.  The  problem  how  thought  can  know  anything 
becomes,  therefore,  as  irrelevant  as  the  problem  how  elements  can 
combine  at  all.  The  recognition  of  this  is  a  great  gain,  and  the 
promise  of  it  most  fruitful  for  both  logic  and  metaphysics. 

But,  as  I  have  tried  to  point  out,  all  this  surrendering  of  pure 
thought  as  opposed  to  pure  reality,  does  not  at  all  necessitate  our 
regarding  judgment  as  a  process  which  makes  reality  different 
from  what  it  was  before.  Of  course  there  is  one  difference,  namely, 
the  logical  one;  for  reality  prior  to  logical  processes  is  unknown.  As 
a  result  of  these  processes  it  becomes  known.  These  processes  are, 
therefore,  responsible  for  a  known  as  distinct  from  an  unknown 
reality.  But  what  is  the  transformation  which  reality  undergoes  in 
becoming  known?  When  it  becomes  known  that  water  seeks  its  own 
level,  what  change  has  taken  place  in  the  water?  It  would  appear 
that  we  must  answer,  none.  The  water  which  seeks  its  own  level  has 
not  been  transformed  into  ideas  or  even  into  a  human  experience. 
It  appears  to  remain,  as  water,  precisely  what  it  was  before.  The 
transformation  which  takes  place,  takes  place  in  the  one  who  knows, 
a  transformation  from  ignorance  to  knowledge.  Psychology  and  bio- 
logy can  afford  us  the  natural  history  of  this  transformation,  but 
they  cannot  inform  us  in  the  least  as  to  why  it  should  have  its 
specific  character.  That  is  given  and  not  deduced.  The  attempts  to 
deduce  it  have,  without  exception,  been  futile.  That  is  why  we  are 
forced  to  take  it  as  ultimate  in  the  same  way  we  take  as  ultimate 
the  specific  character  of  any  definite  transformation.  To  my  mind, 
there  is  needed  a  fuller  and  more  cordial  recognition  of  this  fact.  The 
conditions  under  which  we,  as  individuals,  know  are  certainly  dis- 
coverable, just  as  much  as  the  conditions  under  which  we  breathe 


THE  FIELD   OF   LOGIC  327 

or  digest.  And  what  happens  to  things  when  we  know  them  is  also 
as  discoverable  as  what  happens  to  them  when  we  breathe  them  or 
digest  them. 

But  here  the  ideahst  may  interpose  that  we  can  never  know  what 
happens  to  things  when  we  know  them,  because  we  can  never  know 
them  before  they  become  known.  I  suppose  I  ought  to  wrestle  with 
this  objection.  It  is  an  obvious  one,  but,  to  my  mind,  it  is  without 
force.  The  objection,  if  pursued,  can  carry  us  only  in  a  circle.  The 
problem  of  knowledge  is  still  on  our  hands,  and  every  logician  of 
whatever  school,  the  offerer  of  this  objection  also,  has,  nevertheless, 
attempted  to  show  what  the  transformation  is  that  thought  works, 
for  all  admit  that  it  works  some.  Are  we,  therefore,  engaged  in  a 
hopeless  task?  Or  have  we  failed  to  grasp  the  significance  of  our 
problem?  I  think  the  latter.  We  fail  to  recognize  that,  in  one  way 
or  other,  we  do  solve  the  problem,  and  that  our  attempts  to  solve  it 
show  quite  clearly  that  the  objection  under  consideration  is  without 
force.  Take,  for  instance,  any  concrete  case  of  knowledge,  the  water 
seeking  its  own  level,  again.  Follow  the  process  of  knowledge  to  the 
fullest  extent,  we  never  find  a  single  problem  which  is  not  solvable 
by  reference  to  the  concrete  things  with  which  we  are  dealing,  nor 
a  single  solution  which  is  not  forced  upon  us  by  these  things  rather 
than  by  the  fact  that  we  deal  with  them.  The  transformation  wrought 
is  thus  discovered,  in  the  progress  of  knowledge  itself,  to  be  wrought 
solely  in  the  inquiring  individual,  and  wrought  by  repeated  contact 
with  the  things  with  which  he  deals.  In  other  words,  all  knowledge 
discloses  the  fact  that  its  content  is  not  created  by  itself,  but  by  the 
things  with  which  it  is  concerned. 

It  is  quite  possible,  therefore,  that  knowledge  should  be  what 
we  call  transcendent  and  yet  not  involve  us  in  a  transcendental 
logic.  That  we  should  be  able  to  know  without  altering  the  things  we 
know  is  no  more  and  no  less  remarkable  and  mysterious  than  that 
we  should  be  able  to  digest  by  altering  the  things  we  digest.  In 
other  words,  the  fact  that  digestion  alters  the  things  is  no  reason 
that  knowledge  should  alter  them,  even  if  we  admit  that  logical 
processes  are  vital  and  subject  to  evolution.  Indeed,  if  evolution 
teaches  us  anything  on  this  point,  it  is  that  knowledge  processes  are 
real  just  as  they  exist,  as  real  as  growth  and  digestion,  and  must 
have  their  character  described  in  accordance  with  what  they  are.  The 
recognition  that  knowledge  can  be  transcendent  and  yet  its  processes 
vital  seems  to  throw  light  on  the  difficulty  evolution  has  encountered 
in  accounting  for  consciousness  and  knowledge.  All  the  reactions 
of  the  individual  seem  to  be  expressible  in  terms  of  chemistry  and 
physics  without  calling  in  consciousness  as  an  operating  factor.  What 
is  this  but  the  recognition  of  its  transcendence,  especially  when  the 
conditions  of  conscious  activity  are  quite  likely  expressible  in  chem- 


328  LOGIC 

ical  and  physical  terms?  While,  therefore,  biological  considerations 
result  in  the  great  gain  of  giving  concrete  reality  to  the  processes  of 
knowledge,  the  gain  is  lost,  if  knowledge  itself  is  denied  the  tran- 
scendence which  it  so  evidently  discloses. 

IV 

The  argument  advanced  in  this  discussion  has  had  the  aim  of 
emphasizing  the  fact  that  in  knowledge  we  have  actually  given,  as 
content,  reality  as  it  is  in  independence  of  the  act  of  knowing,  that  the 
real  world  is  self-existent,  independent  of  the  judgments  we  make 
about  it.  This  fact  has  been  emphasized  in  order  to  confine  the 
field  of  logic  to  the  field  of  knowledge  as  thus  understood.  In  the 
course  of  the  argument,  I  have  occasionally  indicated  what  some 
of  the  resulting  problems  of  logic  are.  These  I  wish  now  to  state  in 
a  somewhat  more  systematic  way. 

The  basal  problem  of  logic  becomes,  undoubtedly,  the  metaphysics 
of  knowledge,  the  determination  of  the  nature  of  knowledge  and  its 
relation  to  reality.  It  is  quite  evident  that  this  is  just  the  problem 
which  the  current  tendencies  criticised  have  sought,  not  to  solve, 
but  to  avoid  or  set  aside.  Their  motives  for  so  doing  have  been 
mainly  the  difficulties  which  have  arisen  from  the  Kantian  philo- 
sophy in  its  development  into  transcendentalism,  and  the  desire 
to  extend  the  category  of  evolution  to  embrace  the  whole  of  reality, 
knowledge  included.  I  confess  to  feeling  the  force  of  these  motives 
as  strongly  as  any  advocate  of  the  criticised  opinions.  But  I  do  not 
see  my  way  clear  to  satisfying  them  by  denying  or  explaining  away 
the  evident  character  of  knowledge  itself.  It  appears  far  better 
to  admit  that  a  metaphysics  of  knowledge  is  as  yet  hopeless,  rather 
than  so  to  transform  knowledge  as  to  get  rid  of  the  problem;  for  we 
must  ultimately  ask  after  the  truth  of  the  transformation.  But  I 
am  far  from  believing  that  a  metaphysics  of  knowledge  is  hopeless. 
The  biological  tendencies  themselves  seem  to  furnish  us  with  much 
material  for  at  least  the  beginnings  of  one.  Reality  known  is  to  be  set 
over  against  reality  unknown  or  independent  of  knowledge,  not  as 
image  to  original,  idea  to  thing,  phenomena  to  noumena,  appearance 
to  reality;  but  reality  as  known  is  a  new  stage  in  the  development  of 
reality  itself.  It  is  not  an  external  mind  which  knows  reality  by 
means  of  its  own  ideas,  but  reality  itself  becomes  known  through 
its  own  expanding  and  readjusting  processes.  So  far  I  am  in  entire 
agreement  with  the  tendencies  I  have  criticised.  But  what  change  is 
effected  by  this  expansion  and  readjustment?  I  can  find  no  other 
answer  than  this  simple  one :  the  change  to  knowledge.  And  by  this 
I  mean  to  assert  unequivocally  that  the  addition  of  knowledge  to 
a  reality  hitherto  without  it  is  simply  an  addition  to  it  and  not  a 
transformation  of  it.   Such  a  view  may  appear  to  make  knowledge 


THE  FIELD   OF   LOGIC  329 

a  wholly  useless  addition,  but  I  see  no  inherent  necessity  in  such  a 
conclusion.  Nor  do  I  see  any  inherent  necessity  of  supposing  that 
knowledge  must  be  a  useful  addition.  Yet  I  would  not  be  so  foolish 
as  to  deny  the  usefulness  of  knowledge.  We  have,  of  course,  the 
most  palpable  evidences  of  its  use.  As  we  examine  them,  I  think  we 
find,  without  exception,  that  knowledge  is  useful  just  in  proportion 
as  we  find  that  reality  is  not  transformed  by  being  known.  If  it  really 
were  transformed  in  that  process,  could  anything  else  than  confusion 
result  from  the  multitude  of  knowing  individuals? 

To  me,  therefore,  the  metaphysics  of  the  situation  resolves  itself 
into  the  realistic  position  that  a  developing  reality  develops,  under 
ascertainable  conditions,  into  a  known  realitj'-  without  undergoing 
any  other  transformation,  and  that  this  new  stage  marks  an  advance 
in  the  efficiency  of  reality  in  its  adaptations.  My  confidence  steadily 
grows  that  this  whole  process  can  be  scientifically  worked  out.  It  is 
impossible  here  to  justify  my  confidence  in  detail,  and  I  must  leave 
the  matter  with  the  following  suggestion.  The  point  from  which 
knowledge  starts  and  to  which  it  ultimately  returns  is  always  some 
portion  of  reality  where  there  is  consciousness,  the  things,  namely, 
which,  we  are  wont  to  say,  are  in  consciousness.  These  things  are  not 
ideas  representing  other  things  outside  of  consciousness,  but  real 
things,  which,  by  being  in  consciousness,  have  the  capacity  of  repre- 
senting each  other,  of  standing  for  or  implying  each  other.  Know- 
ledge is  not  the  creation  of  these  implications,  but  their  successful 
systematization.  It  will  be  found,  I  think,  that  this  general  state- 
ment is  true  of  every  concrete  case  of  knowledge  which  we  possess. 
Its  detailed  working  out  would  be  a  metaphysics  of  knowledge,  an 
epistemology. 

Since  knowledge  is  the  successful  systematization  of  the  implica- 
tions which  are  disclosed  in  things  by  virtue  of  consciousness,  a 
second  logical  problem  of  fundamental  importance  is  the  determina- 
tion of  the  most  general  types  of  implication  with  the  categories 
which  underlie  them.  The  execution  of  this  problem  would  naturally 
involve,  as  subsidiary,  the  greater  part  of  formal  and  symbolic  logic. 
Indeed,  vital  doctrines  of  the  syllogism,  of  definition,  of  formal 
inference,  of  the  calculus  of  classes  and  propositions,  of  the  logic  of 
relations,  appear  to  be  bound  up  ultimately  with  a  doctrine  of  cate- 
gories; for  it  is  only  a  recognition  of  basal  types  of  existence  with 
their  implications  that  can  save  these  doctrines  from  mere  formal- 
ism. These  types  of  existence  or  categories  are  not  to  be  regarded 
as  free  creations  or  as  the  contributions  of  the  mind  to  experience. 
There  is  no  deduction  of  them  possible.  They  must  be  discovered 
in  the  actual  progress  of  knowledge  itself,  and  I  see  no  reason  to 
suppose  that  their  number  is  necessarily  fixed,  or  that  we  should 
necessarily  be  in  possession  of  all  of  them.    It  is  requisite,  however, 


330  LOGIC 

that  in  every  case  categories  should  be  incapable  of  reduction  to 
each  other, 

A  doctrine  of  categories  seems  to  me  to  be  of  the  greatest  import- 
ance in  the  systematization  of  knowledge,  for  no  problem  of  relation 
is  even  stateable  correctly  before  the  type  of  existence  to  which  its 
terms  belong  has  been  first  determined.  I  submit  one  illustration 
to  reinforce  this  general  statement,  namely,  the  relation  of  mind  to 
body.  If  mind  and  body  belong  to  the  same  type  of  existence,  we 
have  one  set  of  problems  on  our  hands;  but  if  they  do  not,  we  have 
an  entirely  different  set.  Yet  volumes  of  discussion  written  on  this 
subject  have  abounded  in  confusion,  simply  because  they  have 
regarded  mind  and  body  as  belonging  to  radically  different  types  of 
existence  and  yet  related  in  terms  of  the  type  to  which  one  of  them 
belongs.  The  doctrine  of  parallelism  is,  perhaps,  the  epitome  of  this 
confusion. 

The  doctrine  of  categories  will  involve  not  only  the  greater  part 
of  formal  and  symbolic  logic,  but  will  undoubtedly  carry  the  logician 
into  the  doctrine  of  method.  Here  it  is  to  be  hoped  that  recent 
tendencies  will  result  in  effectively  breaking  down  the  artificial  dis- 
tinctions which  have  prevailed  between  deduction  and  induction. 
Differences  in  method  do  not  result  from  differences  in  points  of  de- 
parture, or  between  the  universal  and  the  particular,  but  from  the 
categories,  again,  which  give  the  method  direction  and  aim,  and 
result  in  different  types  of  synthesis.  In  this  direction,  the  logician 
may  hope  for  an  approximately  correct  classification  of  the  various 
departments  pf  knowledge.  Such  a  classification  is,  perhaps,  the 
ideal  of  logical  theory. 


SECTION  D  —  METHODOLOGY   OF  SCIENCE 


SECTION  D  —  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 


{Hall  6,  September  22,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman:  Professor  James  E.  Creighton,  Cornell  University. 
Speakers:   Professor  Wilhelm  Ostwald,  University  of  Leipzig. 
Professor  Benno  Erdmann,  University  of  Bonn. 
Secretary:  Dr.  R.  B.  Perry,  Harvard  University. 


ON   THE   THEORY  OF   SCIENCE 

BY    WILHELM    OSTWALD 

{Translated  from  the  German  by  Dr.  R.  M.  Yerkes,  Harvard  University) 

[Wilhelm  Ostwald,  Professor  of  Physical  Chemistry,  University  of  Leipzig, 
since  1887.  b.  September  2,  1853,  Riga,  Russia.  Grad.  Candidate  Chemistry, 
1877;  Master  Chemistry,  1878;  Doctor  Chemistry,  Dorpat.  Dr.  Hon. 
Halle  and  Cambridge;  Privy  Councilor;  Assistant,  Dorpat,  1875-81; 
Regular  Professor,  Riga,  1881-87.  Member  various  learned  and  scientific 
societies.  Author  of  Manual  of  General  Chemistry;  Electro  Chemistry;  Foun- 
dation of  Inorganic  Chemistry;  Lectures  on  Philosophy  of  Nature;  Artist's 
Letters;  Essays  and  Lectures;  and  many  other  noted  works  and  papers  on 
Chemistry  and  Philosophy.] 

One  of  the  few  points  on  which  the  philosophy  of  to-day  is  united  is 
the  knowledge  that  the  only  thing  completely  certain  and  undoubted 
for  each  one  is  the  content  of  his  own  consciousness;  and  here  the 
certainty  is  to  be  ascribed  not  to  the  content  of  consciousness  in 
general,  but  only  to  the  momentary  content. 

This  momentary  content  we  divide  into  two  large  groups,  which 
we  refer  to  the  inner  and  outer  world.  If  we  call  any  kind  of  content 
of  consciousness  an  experience,  then  we  ascribe  to  the  outer  world 
such  experiences  as  arise  without  the  activity  of  our  will  and  cannot 
be  called  forth  by  its  activity  alone.  Such  experiences  never  arise 
without  the  activit}''  of  certain  parts  of  our  body,  which  we  call 
sense  organs.  In  other  words,  the  outer  world  is  that  which  reaches 
our  consciousness  through  the  senses. 

On  the  other  hand,  we  ascribe  to  our  inner  world  all  experiences 
which  arise  without  the  immediate  assistance  of  a  sense  organ. 
Here,  first  of  all,  belong  all  experiences  which  we  call  remembering 
and  thinking.  An  exact  and  complete  differentiation  of  the  two 
territories  is  not  intended  here,  for  our  purpose  does  not  demand 
that  this  task  be  undertaken.  For  this  purpose  the  general  orienta- 
tion in  which  every  one  recognizes  familiar  facts  of  his  consciousness 
is  sufficient. 

Each  experience  has  the  characteristic  of  uniqueness.  None  of  us 
doubts  that  the  expression  of  the  poet  "  Everything  is  only  repeated 
in  life"  is  really  just  the  opposite  of  the  truth,  and  that  in  fact  no- 


334  METHODOLOGY   OF   SCIENCE 

thing  is  repeated  in  life.  But  to  express  such  a  judgment  we  must. 
be  in  position  to  compare  different  experiences  with  each  other,  and 
this  possibihty  rests  upon  a  fundamental  phenomenon  of  our  con- 
sciousness, memory.  Memory  alone  enables  us  to  put  various  ex- 
periences in  relation  to  each  other,  so  that  the  question  as  to  their 
likeness  or  difference  can  be  asked. 

We  find  the  simpler  relations  here  in  the  inner  experiences.  A 
certain  thought,  such  as  twice  two  is  four,  I  can  bring  up  in  my 
consciousness  as  often  as  I  wish,  and  in  addition  to  the  content  of 
the  thought  I  experience  the  further  consciousness  that  I  have 
already  had  this  thought  before,  that  it  is  familiar  to  me. 

A  similar  but  somewhat  more  complex  phenomenon  appears  in 
the  experiences  in  which  the  outer  world  takes  part.  After  I  have 
eaten  an  apple,  I  can  repeat  the  experience  in  two  ways.  First,  as 
an  inner  experience,  I  can  remember  that  I  have  eaten  the  apple 
and  by  an  effort  of  my  will  I  can  re-create  in  myself,  although  with. 
diminished  strength  and  intensity,  a  part  of  the  former  experience 
—  the  part  which  belonged  to  my  inner  world.  Another  part,  the 
sense  impression  which  belonged  to  that  experience,  I  cannot  re-create 
by  an  effort  of  my  will,  but  I  must  again  eat  an  apple  in  order  to 
have  a  similar  experience  of  this  sort.  This  is  a  complete  repetition 
of  the  experience  to  which  the  external  world  also  contributes. 
Such  a  repetition  does  not  depend  altogether  on  my  own  powers, 
for  it  is  necessary  that  I  have  an  apple,  that  is,  that  certain  condi- 
tions which  are  independent  of  me  and  belong  to  the  outer  world 
be  fulfilled. 

Whether  the  outer  world  takes  part  in  the  repetition  of  an  experi- 
ence or  not  has  no  influence  upon  the  possibility  of  the  content  of 
consciousness  which  we  call  memory.  From  this  it  follows  that  this 
content  depends  upon  the  inner  experience  alone,  and  that  we 
remember  an  external  event  only  by  means  of  its  inner  constituents. 
The  mere  repetition  of  corresponding  sense  impressions  is  not  suffi- 
cient for  this,  for  we  can  see  the  same  person  repeatedly  without 
recognizing  him,  if  the  inner  accompanying  phenomena  were  so 
insignificant,  as  a  result  of  lack  of  interest,  that  their  repetition 
does  not  produce  the  content  of  consciousness  known  as  memory. 
If  we  see  him  quite  frequently,  the  frequent  repetition  of  the  exter- 
nal impression  finally  causes  the  memory  of  the  corresponding  inner 
experience.  . 

From  this  it  results  that  for  the  "  memory  "-reaction  a  certain 
intensity  of  the  inner  experience  is  necessary.  This  threshold  can  be 
attained  either  at  once  or  by  continued  repetition.  The  repetitions 
are  the  more  effective  the  more  rapidly  they  follow  each  other. 
From  this  we  may  conclude  that  the  memory- value  of  an  experience, 
or  its  capacity  for  calling  forth  the  "  memory  "-reaction  by  repetition, 


ON  THE  THEORY   OF  SCIENCE  335 

decreases  with  the  lapse  of  time.  Further,  we  must  consider  the 
fact  mentioned  above,  that  an  experience  is  never  exactly  repeated, 
and  that  therefore  the  "memory ^'-reaction  occurs  even  where  there 
is  only  resemblance  or  partial  agreement  in  place  of  complete  agree- 
ment. Here,  too,  there  are  diiferent  degrees;  memory  takes  place 
more  easily  the  more  perfectly  the  two  experiences  agree,  and  vice 
versa. 

If  we  look  at  these  phenomena  from  the  physiological  side,  we 
may  say  we  have  two  kinds  of  apparatus  or  organs,  one  of  which 
does  not  depend  upon  our  will,  whereas  the  other  does.  The  former 
are  the  sense  organs,  the  latter  constitutes  the  organ  of  thought. 
Only  the  activities  of  the  latter  constitute  our  experiences  or  the 
content  of  our  consciousness. 

The  activities  of  the  former  may  call  forth  the  corresponding  pro- 
cesses of  the  latter,  but  this  is  not  always  necessary.  Our  sense  organs 
can  be  influenced  without  our  "noticing''  it,  that  is,  without  the 
thinking  apparatus  being  involved.  An  especially  important  reaction 
of  the  thinking  apparatus  is  memory,  that  is,  the  consciousness  that 
an  experience  which  we  have  just  had  possesses  more  or  less  agreement 
with  former  experiences.  With  reference  to  the  organ  of  thought, 
it  is  the  expression  of  the  general  physiological  fact  that  every  process 
influences  the  organ  in  such  a  way  that  it  has  a  different  relation  to 
the  repetition  of  this  process,  from  the  first  time,  and  moreover  that 
the  repetition  is  rendered  easier.   This  influence  decreases  with  time. 

It  is  chiefly  upon  these  phenomena  that  experience  rests.  Experi- 
ence results  from  the  fact  that  all  events  consist  of  a  complete  series  of 
simultaneous  and  successive  components.  When  a  connection  between 
some  of  those  parts  has  become  familiar  to  us  by  the  repetition  of 
similar  occurrences  (for  instance,  the  succession  of  day  and  night),  we 
do  not  feel  such  an  occurrence  as  something  completely  new,  but  as 
something  partially  familiar,  and  the  single  parts  or  phases  of  it  do 
not  surprise  us,  but  rather  we  anticipate  their  coming  or  expect 
them.  From  expectation  to  prediction  is  only  a  short  step,  and  so 
experience  enables  us  to  prophesy  the  future  from  the  past  and  pre- 
sent. 

Now  this  is  also  the  road  to  science;  for  science  is  nothing  but 
systematized  experience,  that  is,  experience  reduced  to  its  simplest 
and  clearest  forms.  Its  purposes  to  predict  from  a  part  of  a  phe- 
nomenon which  is  known  another  part  which  is  not  yet  known. 
Here  it  may  be  a  question  of  spatial  as  well  as  of  temporal  phenom- 
ena. Thus  the  scientij&c  zodlogist  knows  how  to  "determine,"  that 
is,  to  tell,  from  the  skull  of  an  animal,  the  nature  of  the  other  parts 
of  the  animal  to  which  the  skull  belongs;  likewise  the  astronomer 
is  able  to  indicate  the  future  situation  of  a  planet  from  a  few  obser- 
vations of  its  present  situation;  and  the  more  exact  the  first  obser- 


336  METHODOLOGY   OF   SCIENCE 

vations  were,  the  more  distant  the  future  for  which  he  can  predict. 
All  such  scientific  predictions  are  limited,  therefore,  with  reference  to 
their  number  and  their  accuracy.  If  the  skull  shown  to  the  zoologist 
is  that  of  a  chicken,  then  he  will  probably  be  able  to  indicate  the 
general  characteristics  of  chickens,  and  also  perhaps  whether  the 
chicken  had  a  top-knot  or  not;  but  not  its  color,  and  only  uncertainly 
its  age  and  its  size.  Both  facts,  the  possibility  of  prediction  and  its 
limitation  in  content  and  amount,  are  an  expression  for  the  two 
fundamental  facts,  that  among  our  experiences  there  is  similarity, 
but  not  complete  agreement. 

The  foregoing  considerations  deserve  to  be  discussed  and  extended 
in  several  directions.  First,  the  objection  will  be  made  that  a  chicken 
or  a  planet  is  not  an  experience;  we  call  them  rather  by  the  most 
general  name  of  thing.  But  our  knowledge  of  the  chicken  begins 
with  the  experiencing  of  certain  visual  impressions,  to  which  are 
added,  perhaps,  certain  impressions  of  hearing  and  touch.  The 
sight  impressions  (to  discuss  these  first)  by  no  means  completely 
agree.  We  see  the  chicken  large  or  small,  according  to  the  distance; 
and  according  to  its  position  and  movement  its  outline  is  very  differ- 
ent. As  we  have  seen,  however,  these  differences  are  continually 
grading  into  one  other  and  do  not  reach  beyond  certain  limits;  we 
neglect  to  observe  them  and  rest  contented  with  the  fact  that  certain 
other  peculiarities  (legs,  wings,  eyes,  bill,  comb,  etc.)  remain  and  do 
not  change.  The  constant  properties  we  group  together  as  a  thing, 
and  the  changing  ones  we  call  the  states  of  this  thing.  Among. the 
changing  properties,  we  distinguish  further  those  which  depend 
upon  us  (for  example,  the  distance)  and  those  upon  which  we  have 
no  immediate  influence  (for  instance,  the  position  or  motion):  the 
first  is  called  the  subjective  changeable  part  of  our  experience,  while 
the  second  is  called  the  objective  mutability  of  the  thing. 

This  omission  of  both  the  subjectively  and  objectively  changeable 
portion  of  the  experience  in  connection  with  the  retention  of  the 
constant  portion  and  the  gathering  together  of  the  latter  into  a 
unity  is  one  of  the  most  important  operations  which  we  perform 
with  our  experiences.  We  call  it  the  process  of  abstraction,  and  its 
product,  the  permanent  unity,  we  call  a  concept.  Plainly  this  pro- 
cedure contains  arbitrary  as  well  as  necessary  factors.  Arbitrary  or 
accidental  is  the  circumstance  that  quite  different  phases  of  a  given 
experience  come  to  consciousness  according  to  our  attention,  the 
amount  of  practice  we  have  had,  indeed  according  to  our  whole 
intellectual  nature.  We  may  overlook  constant  factors  and  attend 
to  changeable  ones.  The  objective  factors-,  however,  become  neces- 
sary as  soon  as  we  have  noticed  them;  after  we  have  seen  that  the 
chicken  is  black,  it  is  not  in  our  power  to  see  it  red.  Accordingly,  in 
general,  our  knowledge  of  that  which  agrees  must  be  less  than  it 


ON   THE   THEORY    OF    SCIENCE  337 

actually  could  be,  since  we  have  not  been  able  to  observe  ever}^ 
agreement,  and  our  concept  is  always  poorer  in  constituents  at  any 
given  time  than  it  might  be.  To  seek  out  such  elements  of  concepts 
as  have  been  overlooked,  and  to  prove  that  they  are  necessary  factors 
of  the  corresponding  experiences,  is  one  of  the  never-ending  tasks 
of  science.  The  other  case,  namely,  that  elements  have  been  received 
in  the  concept  which  do  not  prove  to  be  constant,  also  happens,  and 
leads  to  another  task.  One  can  then  leave  that  element  out  of  the 
concept,  if  further  experiences  show  that  the  other  elements  are 
found  in  them,  or  one  can  form  a  new  concept  which  contains  the 
former  elements,  leaving  out  those  that  have  been  recognized  as 
unessential.  For  a  long  time  the  white  color  belonged  to  the  concept 
SAvan.  When  the  Dutch  black  swans  became  known,  it  was  possible 
either  to  drop  the  element  white  from  the  concept  swan  (as  actually 
happened),  or  to  make  a  new  concept  for  the  bird  which  is  similar 
to  the  swan  but  black.  Which  choice  is  made  in  a  given  case  is  largely 
arbitrary,  and  is  determined  by  considerations  of  expediency. 

Into  the  formation  of  concepts,  therefore,  two  factors  are  operat- 
ive, an  objective  empirical  factor,  and  a  subjective  or  purposive 
factor.  The  fitness  of  a  concept  is  seen  in  relation  to  its  purpose, 
which  we  shall  now  consider. 

The  purpose  of  a  concept  is  its  use  for  prediction.  The  old  logic 
set  up  the  syllogism  as  the  type  of  thought-activity,  and  its  simplest 
example  is  the  well-known 

All  men  are  mortal, 

Caius  is  a  man,  ;   ; 

Therefore  Caius  is  mortal. 

In  general,  the  scheme  runs  s,,,-. ' 

To  the  concept  M  belongs  the  element  B, 
C  belongs  under  the  concept  M, 
Therefore  the  element  B  is  found  in  C. 

One  can  say  that  this  method  of  reasoning  is  in  regular  use  even: 
to  this  day.  It  must  be  added,  however,  that  this  use  is  of  a  quite 
different  nature  from  that  of  the  ancients.  Whereas  formerly  the- 
setting  up  of  the  first  proposition  or  the  major  premise  was  con- 
sidered the  most  important  thing,  and  the  establishment  of  the 
second  proposition  or  minor  premise  was  thought  to  be  a  rather 
trifling  matter,  now  the  relation  is  reversed.  The  major  premise  con- 
tains the  description  of  a  concept,  the  minor  makes  the  assertion 
that  a  certain  thing  belongs  under  this  concept.  What  right  exists; 
for  such  an  assertion?  The  most  palpable  reply  would  be,  since- 
all  the  elements  of  the  concept  M  (including  B)  are  found  in  C,  G 
belongs  under  the  concept  M.  Such  a  conclusion  would  indeed  be 
binding,  but  at  the  same  time  quite  worthless,  for  it  only  repeats  the 


338  METHODOLOGY   OF   SCIENCE 

minor  premise.  Actually  the  method  of  reasoning  is  essentially 
different,  for  the  minor  premise  is  not  obtained  by  showing  that  all 
the  elements  of  the  concept  M  are  found  in  C,  but  only  some  of  them. 
The  conclusion  is  not  necessary,  but  only  probable,  and  the  whole 
process  of  reasoning  runs :  Certain  elements  are  frequently  found  to- 
gether, therefore  they  are  united  in  the  concept  M.  Certain  of  these 
elements  are  recognized  in  the  thing  C,  therefore  probably  the  other 
elements  of  the  concept  M  will  be  found  in  C. 

The  old  logic,  also,  was  familiar  with  this  kind  of  conclusion.  It 
was  branded,  however,  as  the  worst  of  all,  by  the  name  of  incomplete 
induction,  since  the  absolute  certainty  demanded  of  the  syllogism 
did  not  belong  to  its  results.  One  must  admit,  however,  that  the  whole 
of  modern  science  makes  use  of  no  other  form  of  reasoning  than 
incomplete  induction,  for  it  alone  admits  of  a  prediction,  that  is,  an 
indication  of  relations  which  have  not  been  immediately  observed. 

How  does  science  get  along  with  the  defective  certainty  of  this 
process  of  reasoning?  The  answer  is,  that  the  probability  of  the 
conclusion  can  run  through  all  degrees  from  mere  conjecture  to  the 
maximum  probability,  which  is  practically  indistinguishable  from 
certainty.  The  probability  is  the  greater  the  more  frequently  an 
incomplete  induction  of  this  kind  has  proven  correct  in  later  experi- 
ence. Accordingly  we  have  at  our  command  a  number  of  expressions 
which  in  their  simplest  and  most  general  form  have  the  appearance : 
If  an  element  A  is  met  within  a  thing,  then  the  element  B  is  also 
found  in  it  (in  spatial  or  temporal  relationship). 

If  the  relation  is  temporal,  this  general  statement  is  known  by 
some  such  name  as  the  law  of  causality.  If  it  is  spatial,  one  talks  of 
the  idea  (in  the  Platonic  sense) ,  or  the  type  of  the  thing,  of  substance, 
etc. 

From  the  considerations  here  presented  we  get  an  easy  answer 
to  many  questions  which  are  frequently  discussed  in  very  different 
senses.  First,  the  question  concerning  the  general  validity  of  the 
law  of  causality.  All  attempts  to  prove  such  a  validity  have  failed, 
and  there  has  remained  only  the  indication  that  without  this  law 
we  should  feel  an  unbearable  uncertainty  in  reference  to  the  world. 
From  this,  however,  we  see  very  plainly  that  here  it  is  merely  a 
question  of  expediency.  From  the  continuous  flux  of  our  experiences 
we  hunt  out  those  groups  which  can  always  be  found  again,  in  order 
to  be  able  to  conclude  that  if  the  element  A  is  given,  the  element  B 
will  be  present.  We  do  not  find  this  relationship  as  "given,"  but 
we  put  it  into  our  experiences,  in  that  we  consider  the  parts  which 
correspond  to  the  relationship  as  belonging  together. 

The  very  same  thing  may  be  said  of  spatial  complexes.  Such  factors 
as  are  always,  or  at  any  rate  often,  found  together  are  taken  by  us  as 
"belonging  together,"  and  out  of  them  a  concept  is  formed  which 


ON   THE  THEORY   OF   SCIENCE  339 

embraces  these  factors.  A  question  as  to  the  why  has  here,  as  with 
the  temporal  complexes,  no  definite  meaning.  There  are  countless 
things  that  happen  together  once  to  which  we  pay  no  attention 
because  they  happen  only  once  or  but  seldom.  The  knowledge 
of  the  fact  that  such  a  single  concurrence  exists  amounts  to  nothing, 
since  from  the  presence  of  one  factor  it  does  not  lead  to  a  conclusion 
as  to  the  presence  of  another,  and  therefore  does  not  make  possible 
prediction.  Of  all  the  possible,  and  even  actual  combinations,  only 
those  interest  us  which  are  repeated,  and  this  arbitrary  but  expedient 
selection  produces  the  impression  that  the  world  consists  only  of 
combinations  that  can  be  repeated  ;  that,  in  other  words,  the  law  of 
causality  or  of  the  type  is  a  general  one.  However  general  or  limited 
application  these  laws  have,  is  more  a  question  of  our  skill  in  finding 
the  constant  combinations  among  those  that  are  present  than  a  ques- 
tion of  objective  natural  fact. 

Thus  we  see  the  development  and  pursuit  of  all  sciences  going  on  in 
such  a  way  that  on  the  one  hand  more  and  more  constant  combina- 
tions are  discovered,  and  on  the  other  hand  more  inclusive  relations 
of  this  kind  are  found  out,  by  means  of  which  elements  are  united 
with  each  other  which  before  no  one  had  even  tried  to  bring  together. 
So  sciences  are  increasing  both  in  the  sense  of  an  increasing  complica- 
tion and  in  an  increasing  unification. 

If  we  consider  from  this  standpoint  the  development  and  procedure 
of  the  various  sciences,  we  find  a  rational  division  of  the  sum  total  of 
science  in  the  question  as  to  the  scope  and  multiplicity  of  the  com- 
binations or  groups  treated  of  in  them.  These  two  properties  are  in 
a  certain  sense  antithetical.  The  simpler  a  complex  is,  that  is,  the 
fewer  elements  brought  together  in  it,  the  more  frequently  it  is  met 
with,  and  vice  versa.  One  can  therefore  arrange  all  the  sciences  in 
such  a  way  that  one  begins  with  the  least  multiplicity  and  the  greatest 
scope,  and  ends  with  the  greatest  multiplicity  and  the  least  scope. 
The  first  science  will  be  the  most  general,  and  will  therefore  contain 
the  most  general  and  therefore  the  most  barren  concepts;  the  last 
will  contain  the  most  specific  and  therefore  the  richest. 

What  are  these  limiting  concepts?  The  most  general  is  the  concept 
of  thing,  that  is,  any  piece  of  experience,  seized  arbitrarily  from  the 
flux  of  our  experiences,  which  can  be  repeated.  The  most  specific 
and  richest  is  the  concept  of  human  intercourse.  Between  the  science 
of  things  and  the  science  of  human  intercourse,  all  the  other  sciences 
are  found  arranged  in  regular  gradation.  If  one  follows  out  the 
scheme  the  following  outline  results: 

1.  Theory  of  order.  ~] 

2.  Theory  of  numbers,  or  arithmetic.    !   ^.^  ,, 

„    ^1  . ,.  V  Mathematics.    . 

6.   iheory  of  time. 

4,  Theory  of  space,  or  geometry.         J 


340  METHODOLOGY   OF   SCIENCE 

5.  Mechanics.  ^ 

6.  Physics.        V  Energetics, 

7.  Chemistry,  j 

8.  Physiology.    ] 

9.  Psychology.  V  Biology. 
10.  Sociology.     J 

This  table  is  arbitrary  in  so  far  as  the  grades  assumed  can  be 
increased  or  diminished  according  to  need.  For  example,  mechanics 
and  physics  could  be  taken  together;  or  between  physics  and  chem- 
istry, physical  chemistry  could  be  inserted.  Likewise  between 
physiology  and  psychology,  anthropology  might  find  a  place;  or  the 
first  five  sciences  might  be  united  under  mathematics.  How  one 
makes  these  divisions  is  entirely  a  practical  question,  which  will  be 
answered  at  any  time  in  accordance  with  the  purposes  of  division; 
and  dispute  concerning  the  matter  is  almost  useless. 

I  should  like,  however,  to  call  attention  to  the  three  great  groups 
of  mathematics,  energetics,  and  biology  (in  the  wider  sense).  They 
represent  the  decisive  regulative  thought  which  humanity  has 
evolved,  contributed  up  to  this  time,  toward  the  scientific  mastery  of 
its  experiences.  Arrangement  is  the  fundamental  thought  of  mathe- 
matics. From  mechanics  to  chemistry  the  concept  of  energy  is  the 
most  important;  and  for  the  last  three  sciences  it  is  the  concept  of 
life.  Mathematics,  energetics,  and  biology,  therefore,  embrace  the 
totality  of  the  sciences. 

Before  we  enter  upon  the  closer  consideration  of  these  sciences,  it 
will  be  well  to  anticipate  another  objection  which  can  be  raised  on  the 
basis  of  the  following  fact.  Besides  the  sciences  named  (and  those 
which  lie  between  them)  there  are  many  others,  as  geology,  history, 
medicine,  philology,  which  we  find  difficulty  in  arranging  in  the  above 
scheme,  which  must,  however,  be  taken  into  consideration  in  some 
way  or  other.  They  are  often  characterized  by  the  fact  that  they 
stand  in  relation  with  several  of  the  sciences  named,  but  even  more 
by  the  following  circumstance.  Their  task  is  not,  as  is  true  of  the 
pure  sciences  above  named,  the  discovery  of  general  relationships, 
but  they  relate  rather  to  existing  complex  objects  whose  origin, 
scope,  extent,  etc.,  in  short,  whose  temporal  and  spatial  relationships 
they  have  to  discover  or  to  "explain."  For  this  purpose  they  make 
use  of  relations  which  are  placed  at  their  disposal  by  the  first-named 
pure  sciences.  These  sciences,  therefore,  had  better  be  called  applied 
sciences.  However,  in  this  connection  we  should  not  think  only  or 
even  chiefly  of  technical  applications;  rather  the  expression  is  used 
to  indicate  that  the  reciprocal  relations  of  the  parts  of  an  object  are 
to  be  called  to  mind  by  the  application  of  the  general  rules  found  in 
pure  science. 

While  in  such  a  task  the  abstraction  process  of  pure  science  is 


ON   THE  THEORY  OF   SCIENCE  341 

not  applicable  (for  the  omission  of  certain  parts  and  the  concentra- 
tion upon  others  which  is  characteristic  of  these  is  excluded  by  the 
nature  of  the  task),  yet  in  a  given  case  usually  the  necessity  of  bringing 
in  various  pure  sciences  for  the  purpose  of  explanation  is  evident. 

Astronomy  is  one  of  these  applied  sciences.  Primarily  it  rests  upon 
mechanics,  and  in  its  instrumental  portion,  upon  optics;  in  its 
present  development  on  the  spectroscopic  side,  however,  it  borrows 
considerably  of  chemistry.  In  like  manner  history  is  applied  sociology 
and  psychology.  Medicine  makes  use  of  all  the  sciences  before  men- 
tioned, up  to  psychology,  etc. 

It  is  important  to  get  clearly  in  mind  the  nature  of  these  sciences, 
since,  on  account  of  their  compound  nature,  they  resist  arrangement 
amongst  the  pure  sciences,  while,  on  account  of  their  practical 
significance,  they  still  demand  consideration.  The  latter  fact  gives 
them  also  a  sort  of  arbitrary  or  accidental  character,  since  their 
development  is  largely  conditioned  by  the  special  needs  of  the  time. 
Their  number,  speaking  in  general,  is  very  large,  since  each  pure 
science  may  be  turned  into  an  applied  science  in  various  ways;  and 
since  in  addition  we  have  combinations  of  two,  three,  or  more  sciences. 
Moreover,  the  method  of  procedure  in  the  applied  sciences  is  funda- 
mentally different  from  that  in  the  pure  sciences.  In  the  first  it  is 
a  question  of  the  greatest  possible  analysis  of  a  single  given  complex 
into  its  scientifically  comprehensible  parts;  while  pure  science,  on 
the  other  hand,  considers  many  complexes  together  in  order  to 
separate  out  from  them  their  common  element,  but  expressly  dis- 
claims the  complete  analysis  of  a  single  complex. 

In  scientific  work,  as  it  appears  in  practice,  pure  and  applied 
science  are  by  no  means  sharply  separated.  On  the  one  hand  the 
auxiliaries  of  investigations,  such  as  apparatus,  books,  etc.,  demand 
of  the  pure  investigator  knowledge  and  application  in  applied  science; 
and,  on  the  other  hand,  the  applied  scientist  is  frequently  unable  to 
accomplish  his  task  unless  he  himself  becomes  for  the  time  being 
a  pure  investigator  and  ascertains  or  discovers  the  missing  general 
relationships  which  he  needs  for  his  task.  A  separation  and  differentia- 
tion of  the  two  forms  of  science  was  necessary,  however,  since  the 
method  and  the  aim  of  each  present  essential  differences. 

In  order  to  consider  the  method  of  procedure  of  pure  science  more 
carefully,  let  us  turn  back  to  the  table  on  pages  339, 340,  and  attend  to 
the  single  sciences  separately.  The  theory  of  arrangement  was  men- 
tioned first,  although  this  place  is  usually  assigned  to  mathematics. 
However,  mathematics  has  to  do  with  the  concepts  of  number  and 
magnitude  as  fundamentals,  while  the  theory  of  arrangement  does 
not  make  use  of  these.  Here  the  fundamental  concept  is  rather  the 
thing  or  object  of  which  nothing  more  is  demanded  or  considered 
than  that  it  is  a  fragment  of  our  experience  which  can  be  isolated  and 


342  METHODOLOGY   OF   SCIENCE 

will  remain  so.  It  must  not  be  an  arbitrary  combination;  such  a 
thing  would  have  only  momentary  duration,  and  the  task  of  science, 
to  learn  the  unknown  from  the  given,  could  not  find  appUcation. 
Rather  must  this  element  have  such  a  nature  that  it  can  be  charac- 
terized and  recognized  again,  that  is,  it  must  already  have  a  concept- 
ual nature.  Therefore  only  parts  of  our  experience  which  can  be 
repeated  (which  alone  can  be  objects  of  science)  can  be  characterized 
as  things  or  objects.  But  in  saying  this  we  have  said  all  that  was 
demanded  of  them.  In  other  respects  they  may  be  just  as  different 
as  is  conceivable. 

If  the  question  is  asked.  What  can  be  said  scientifically  about 
indefinite  things  of  this  sort?  it  is  especially  the  relations  of  arrange- 
ment and  association  which  yield  an  answer.  If  we  call  any  definite 
combination  of  such  things  a  group,  we  can  arrange  such  a  group 
in  different  ways,  that  is,  we  can  determine  for  each  thing  the  relation 
in  which  it  is  to  stand  to  the  neighboring  thing.  From  every  such 
arrangement  result  not  only  the  relationships  indicated,  but  a  great 
number  of  new  ones,  and  it  appears  that  when  the  first  relationships 
are  given  the  others  always  follow  in  like  manner.  This,  however, 
is  the  type  of  the  scientific  proposition  or  natural  law  (page  335). 
From  the  presence  of  certain  relations  of  arrangement  we  can  deduce 
the  presence  of  others  which  we  have  not  yet  demonstrated. 

To  illustrate  this  fact  by  an  example,  let  us  think  of  the  things 
arranged  in  a  simple  row,  while  we  choose  one  thing  as  a  first  member 
and  associate  another  with  it  as  following  it;  with  the  latter  another 
is  associated,  etc.  Thereby  the  position  of  each  thing  in  the  row  is 
determined  only  in  relation  to  the  immediately  preceding  thing. 
Nevertheless,  the  position  of  every  member  in  the  whole  row,  and 
therefore  its  relation  to  every  other  member,  is  determined  by  this. 
This  is  seen  in  a  number  of  special  laws.  If  w^e  differentiate  former 
and  latter  members  we  can  formulate  the  proposition,  among  others, 
if  B  is  a  later  member  with  reference  to  A,  and  C  with  reference  to 
B,  then  C  is  also  a  later  member  wdth  reference  to  A. 

The  correctness  and  validity  of  this  proposition  seems  to  us  beyond 
all  doubt.  But  this  is  only  a  result  of  the  fact  that  we  are  able  to 
demonstrate  it  very  easily  in  countless  single  cases,  and  have  so 
demonstrated  it.  We  know  only  cases  which  correspond  to  the 
proposition,  and  have  never  experienced  a  contradictory  case.  To  call 
such  a  proposition,  however,  a  necessity  of  thinking,  does  not  appear 
to  me  correct.  For  the  expression  necessity  of  thinking  can  only  rest 
upon  the  fact  that  every  time  the  proposition  is  thought,  that  is,  every 
time  one  remembers  its  demonstration,  its  confirmation  always  arises. 
But  every  sort  of  false  proposition  is  also  thinkable.  An  undeniable 
proof  of  this  is  the  fact  that  so  much  which  is  false  is  actually  thought. 
But  to  base  the  proof  for  the  correctness  of  a  proposition  upon  the 


ON  THE  THEORY   OF   SCIENCE  343 

impossibility  of  thinking  its  opposite  is  an  impossible  undertaking, 
because  every  sort  of  nonsense  can  be  thought :  where  the  proof  was 
thought  to  have  been  given,  there  has  always  been  a  confusion  of 
thought  and  intuition,  proof  or  inspection. 

With  this  one  proposition  of  course  the  theory  of  order  is  not 
exhausted,  for  here  it  is  not  a  question  of  the  development  of  this 
theory,  but  of  an  example  of  the  nature  of  the  problems  of  science. 
Of  the  further  questions  we  shall  briefly  discuss  the  problem  of 
association. 

If  we  have  two  groups  A  and  B  given,  one  can  associate  with  every 
member  of  A  one  of  B;  that  is,  we  determine  that  certain  operations 
which  can  be  carried  on  with  the  members  of  A  are  also  to  be  carried 
on  with  those  of  B.  Now  we  can  begin  by  simply  carrying  out  the 
association,  member  for  member.  Then  we  shall  have  one  of  three 
results:  A  will  be  exhausted  while  there  are  still  members  of  B  left, 
or  B  will  be  exhausted  first,  or  finally  A  and  B  will  be  exhausted  at 
the  same  time.  In  the  first  case  we  call  A  poorer  than  B;  in  the  second 
B  poorer  than  A;  in  the  third  both  quantities  are  alike. 

Here  for  the  first  time  we  come  upon  the  scientific  concept  of 
equality,  which  calls  for  discussion.  There  can  be  no  question  of  a 
complete  identity  of  the  two  groups  which  have  been  denominated 
equal,  for  we  have  made  the  assumption  that  the  members  of  both 
groups  can  be  of  any  nature  whatever.  They  can  then  be  as  different 
as  possible,  considered  singly,  but  they  are  alike  as  groups.  However 
I  may  arrange  the  members  of  A,  I  can  make  a  similar  arrangement 
of  the  members  of  B,  since  every  member  of  A  has  one  of  B  associated 
with  it;  and  with  reference  to  the  property  of  arrangement  there  is  no 
difference  to  be  observed  between  A  and  B.  If,  however,  A  is  poorer 
or  richer  than  B,  this  possibility  ceases,  for  then  one  of  the  groups 
has  members  to  which  none  of  the  members  in  the  other  group  cor- 
responds; so  that  the  operations  carried  out  with  these  members 
cannot  be  carried  out  with  those  of  the  other  group. 

Equality  in  the  scientific  sense,  therefore,  means  equivalence, 
or  the  possibility  of  substitution  in  quite  definite  operations  or  for 
quite  definite  relations.  Beyond  this  the  things  which  are  called 
like  may  show  any  differences  whatever.  The  general  scientific 
process  of  abstraction  is  again  easily  seen  in  this  special  case. 

On  the  basis  of  the  definitions  just  given,  we  can  establish  further 
propositions.  If  group  A  equals  B,  and  B  equals  C,  then  A  also 
equals  C.  The  proof  of  this  is  that  we  can  relate  every  member 
of  A  to  a  correspanding  member  of  B  and  by  hypothesis  no 
member  will  be  left.  Then  C  is  arranged  with  reference  to  B,  and 
here  also  no  member  is  left.  By  this  process  every  member  of  A, 
through  the  connecting  link  of  a  member  of  B,  is  associated  with 
a  member  of  C;  and  this  association  i-s  preserved  even  if  we  cut  out 


344  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

the  group  B.  Therefore  A  and  C  are  equal.  The  same  process  of 
reasoning  can  be  carried  out  for  any  number  of  groups. 

Likewise  it  can  be  demonstrated  that  if  A  is  poorer  than  B  and  B 
poorer  than  C,  then  A  is  also  poorer  than  C.  For  in  the  association 
of  B  with  A  some  members  of  B  are  left  over  by  hypothesis,  and 
likewise  some  members  of  C  are  left  over  if  one  associates  C  with  B. 
Therefore  in  the  association  of  C  with  A,  not  only  those  members  are 
left  over  which  could  not  be  associated  with  B,  but  also  those  mem- 
bers of  C  which  extend  beyond  B.  This  proposition  can  be  extended 
to  any  number  of  groups,  and  permits  the  arrangement  of  a  number 
of  different  groups  in  a  simple  series  by  beginning  with  the  poorest 
and  choosing  each  following  so  that  it  is  richer  than  the  preceding 
but  poorer  than  the  following.  From  the  proposition  just  established, 
it  follows  that  every  group  is  so  arranged  with  reference  to  all  other 
groups  that  it  is  richer  than  all  the  preceding  and  poorer  than  all  the 
following.^ 

In  this  derivation  of  scientific  proposition  or  laws  of  the  simplest 
kinds,  the  process  of  derivation  and  the  nature  of  the  result  becomes 
particularly  clear.  We  arrive  at  such  a  proposition  by  performing 
an  operation  and  expressing  the  result  of  it.  This  expression  enables 
us  to  avoid  the  repetition  of  the  operation  in  the  future,  since  in 
accordance  with  the  law  we  can  indicate  the  result  immediately. 
Thus  an  abbreviation  and  therefore  a  facihtation  of  the  problem  is 
attained  which  is  the  more  considerable  the  larger  the  number  of 
operations  saved. 

If  we  have  a  number  of  equal  groups,  we  know  by  the  process  of 
association  that  all  of  the  operations  with  reference  to  arrangement 
which  we  can  perform  with  one  of  them  can  be  performed  with  all  the 
others.  It  is  sufficient,  therefore,  to  determine  the  properties  of 
arrangement  of  one  of  these  groups  in  order  to  know  forthwith  the 
properties  of  all  the  others.  This  is  an  extremely  important  pro- 
position, which  is  continually  employed  for  the  most  various  purposes. 
All  speaking,  writing,  and  reading  rests  upon  the  association  of 
thoughts  with  sounds  and  symbols,  and  by  arranging  the  signs  in 
accordance  with  our  thoughts  we  bring  it  to  pass  that  our  hearers 
or  readers  think  like  thoughts  in  like  order.  In  a  similar  fashion  we 
make  use  of  various  systems  of  formulae  in  the  different  sciences, 
especially  in  the  simpler  sciences;  and  these  formulae  we  correlate 
with  phenomena  and  use  in  place  of  the  phenomena  themselves, 
and  can  therefore  derive  from  them  certain  characteristics  of  phe- 
nomena without  being  compelled  to  use  the  latter.  The  force  of  this 
process  appears  very  strikingly  in  astronomy  where,  by  the  use  of 
definite  formulae  associated  with  the  different  heavenly  bodies,  we 

1  Equal  groups  cannot  be  distinguished  here,  and  therefore  represent  only  a 
group. 


ON  THE  THEORY  OF  SCIENCE  345 

can  foretell  the  future  positions  of  these  bodies  with  a  high  degree  of 
approximation. 

From  the  theory  of  order  we  come  to  the  theory  of  number  or 
arithmetic  by  the  systematic  arrangement  or  development  of  an 
operation  just  indicated  (page  343).  We  can  arrange  any  number  of 
groups  in  such  a  way  that  a  richer  always  follows  a  poorer.  But  the 
complex  obtained  in  this  manner  is  always  accidental  with  reference 
to  the  number  and  the  richness  of  its  members.  A  regular  and  com- 
plete structure  of  all  possible  groups  is  evidently  obtained  only  if 
we  start  from  a  group  of  one  member  or  from  a  simple  thing,  and  by 
the  addition  of  one  member  at  a  time  make  further  groups  out  of 
those  that  we  have.  Thus  we  obtain  different  groups  arranged  ac- 
cording to  an  increasing  richness,  and  since  we  have  advanced  one 
member  at  a  time,  that  is,  made  the  smallest  step  which  is  possible, 
w^e  are  certain  that  we  have  left  out  no  possible  group,  which  is  poorer 
than  the  richest  to  which  the  operation  has  been  carried. 

This  whole  process  is  familiar;  it  gives  the  series  of  the  positive 
whole  numbers,  that  is,  the  cardinal  numbers.  It  is  to  be  noted  that 
the  concept  of  quantity  has  not  yet  been  considered;  what  we  have 
gained  is  the  concept  of  number.  The  single  things  or  members  in 
this  number  are  quite  arbitrary,  and  especially  they  do  not  need  to 
be  alike  in  any  manner.  Every  number  forms  a  group-type,  and 
arithmetic  or  the  science  of  numbers  has  the  task  of  investigating 
the  properties  of  these  different  types  with  reference  to  their  division 
and  combination.  If  this  is  done  in  general  form,  without  attention 
to  the  special  amount  of  the  number,  the  corresponding  science  is 
called  algebra.  On  the  other  hand,  by  the  application  of  formal  rules 
of  formation,  the  number  system  has  had  one  extension  after  another 
beyond  the  territory  of  its  original  validity.  Thus  counting  back- 
ward led  to  zero  and  to  the  negative  numbers;  the  inversion  of 
involution  to  the  imaginary  numbers.  For  the  group-type  of  the 
positive  whole  numbers  is  the  simplest  but  by  no  means  the  only 
possible  one,  and  for  the  purpose  of  representing  other  manifolds 
than  those  which  are  met  with  in  experience,  these  new  types  have 
proved  themselves  very  useful. 

At  the  same  time  the  number  series  gives  us  an  extremely  useful 
type  of  arrangement.  In  the  process  of  arising  it  is  already  ordered, 
and  w^e  make  use  of  it  for  the  purpose  of  arranging  other  groups. 
Thus,  we  are  accustomed  to  furnish  the  pages  in  a  book,  the  seats  in  a 
theatre,  and  countless  other  groups  which  we  wish  to  make  use  of  in 
any  kind  of  order  with  the  signs  of  the  number  series,  and  thereby 
we  make  the  tacit  assumption  that  the  use  of  that  corresponding 
group  shall  take  place  in  the  same  order  as  the  natural  numbers 
follow  each  other.  The  ordinal  numbers  arising  therefrom  do  not 
represent  quantities,  nor  do  they  represent  the  only  possible  type 


346  METHODOLOGY   OF   SCIENCE 

of  arrangement,  but  they  are  again  the  simplest  of  all.  We  come 
to  the  concept  of  magnitude  only  in  the  theory  of  time  and  space. 
The  theory  of  time  has  not  been  developed  as  a  special  science;  on 
the  contrary,  what  we  have  to  say  about  time  first  appears  in  me- 
chanics. Meantime  we  can  present  the  fundamental  concepts,  which 
arise  in  this  connection,  with  reference  to  such  well-known  charac- 
teristics of  time  that  the  lack  of  a  special  science  of  time  is  no  dis- 
advantage. 

The  first  and  most  important  characteristic  of  time  (and  of  space, 
too)  is  that  it  is  a  continuous  manifold;  that  is,  every  portion  of 
time  chosen  can  be  divided  at  any  place  whatever.  In  the  number 
series  this  is  not  the  case;  it  can  be  divided  only  between  the  single 
numbers.  The  series  one  to  ten  has  only  nine  places  of  division  and 
no  more.  A  minute,  or  a  second,  on  the  other  hand,  has  an  unlimited 
number  of  places  of  division.  In  other  words,  there  is  nothing  in  the 
lapse  of  any  time  which  hinders  us  from  separating  or  distinguishing 
in  thought  at  any  given  instant  the  time  which  has  elapsed  till  then 
from  the  following  time.  It  is  just  the  same  with  space,  except  that 
time  is  a  simple  manifold  and  space  a  threefold,  continuous  manifold. 

Nevertheless,  when  we  measure  them,  we  are  accustomed  to  indicate 
times  and  spaces  with  numbers.  If  we  first  examine,  for  example,  the 
process  of  measuring  a  length,  it  consists  in  our  applying  to  the  dis- 
tance to  be  measured  a  length  conceived  as  unchangeable,  the  unit 
of  measure,  until  we  have  passed  over  the  distance.  The  number  of 
these  applications  gives  us  the  measure  or  magnitude  of  the  distance. 
The  result  is  that  by  the  indication  of  arbitrarily  chosen  points  upon 
the  continuous  distance,  we  place  upon  it  an  artificial  discontinuity 
which  enables  us  to  associate  it  with  the  discontinuous  number  series. 

A  still  further  assumption,  however,  belongs  to  the  concept  of 
measuring,  namely,  that  the  parts  of  the  distance  cut  off  by  the  unit 
used  as  a  measure  be  equal,  and  it  is  taken  for  granted  that  this 
requirement  will  be  fulfilled  to  whatever  place  the  unit  of  measure 
is  shifted.  As  may  be  seen,  this  is  a  definition  of  equality  carried 
further  than  the  former,  for  one  cannot  actually  replace  a  part  of 
the  distance  by  another  in  order  to  convince  one's  self  that  it  has 
not  changed.  Just  as  little  can  one  assert  or  prove  that  the  unit  of 
measure  in  changing  its  place  in  space  remains  of  the  same  length; 
we  can  only  say  that  such  distances  as  are  determined  by  the  unit  of 
measure  in  different  places  are  declared  or  defined  as  equal.  Actually, 
for  our  eye,  the  unit  of  measure  becomes  smaller  in  perspective  the 
farther  away  from  it  we  find  ourselves. 

From  this  example  we  see  again  the  great  contribution  which 
arbitrariness  or  free  choice  has  made  to  all  our  structure  of  science. 
We  could  develop  a  geometry  in  which  distances  which  seem  sub- 
jectively equal  to  our  eye  are  called  equal,  and  upon  this  assumption 


ON  THE  THEORY  OF  SCIENCE  347 

we  would  be  able  to  develop  a  self-consistent  system  or  science.  Such 
a  geometry,  however,  would  have  an  extremely  complex  and  imprac- 
tical structure  for  objective  purposes  (as,  for  example,  land  meas- 
urement), and  so  we  strive  to  develop  a  science  as  free  as  possible 
from  subjective  factors.  Historically,  we  have  before  us  a  process  of 
this  sort  in  the  astronomy  of  Ptolemy  and  that  of  Copernicus.  The 
former  corresponded  to  the  subjective  appearances  in  the  assumption 
that  all  heavenly  bodies  revolved  around  the  earth,  but  proved  to  be 
very  complicated  when  confronted  with  the  task  of  mastering  these 
movements  with  figures.  The  latter  gave  up  the  subjective  stand- 
point of  the  observer,  who  looked  upon  himself  as  the  centre,  and 
attained  a  tremendous  simplification  by  placing  the  centre  of  revo- 
lution in  the  sun. 

A  few  words  are  to  be  said  here  about  the  application  of  arithmetic 
and  algebra  to  geometry.  It  is  well  known  that  under  definite 
assumptions  (coordinates),  geometrical  figures  can  be  represented 
by  means  of  algebraic  formulse,  so  that  the  geometrical  properties 
of  the  figure  can  be  deduced  from  the  arithmetical  properties  of  the 
formulse,  and  vice  versa.  The  question  must  be  asked  how  such  a 
close  and  univocal  relationship  is  possible  between  things  of  such 
different  nature.  The  answer  is,  that  here  is  an  especially  clear  case 
of  association.  The  manifold  of  numbers  is  much  greater  than  that  of 
surface  or  space,  for  while  the  latter  are  determined  by  two  or  three  in- 
dependent measurements,  one  can  have  any  number  of  independent 
number  series  working  together.  Therefore  the  manifold  of  numbers 
is  arbitrarily  limited  to  two  or  three  independent  series,  and  in  so 
far  determines  their  mutual  relations  (by  means  of  the  laws  of  cosine) 
that  there  results  a  manifold,  corresponding  to  the  spatial,  which  can 
be  completely  associated  with  the  spatial  manifold.  Then  we  have 
two  manifolds  of  the  same  manifold  character,  and  all  characteristics 
of  arrangement  and  size  of  the  one  find  their  likeness  in  the  other. 

This  again  characterizes  an  extremely  important  scientific  pro- 
cedure which  consists,  namely,  in  constructing  a  formal  manifold  for 
the  content  of  experience  of  a  certain  field,  to  which  one  attributes 
the  same  manifold  character  which  the  former  possesses.  Every 
science  reaches  by  this  means  a  sort  of  formal  language  of  correspond- 
ing completeness,  which  depends  upon  how  accurately  the  manifold 
character  of  the  object  is  recognized  and  how  judiciously  the  formulse 
have  been  chosen.  While  in  arithmetic  and  algebra  this  task  has  been 
performed  fairly  well  (though  by  no  means  absolutely  perfectly),  the 
chemical  formulse,  for  instance,  express  only  a  relatively  small  part 
of  the  manifold  to  be  represented;  and  in  biology  as  far  as  sociology, 
scarcely  the  first  attempts  have  been  made  in  the  accomplishment  of 
this  task. 

Language  especially  serves  as  such  a  universal  manifold  to  repre- 


348  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

sent  the  manifolds  of  experience.  As  a  result  of  its  development 
from  a  time  of  less  culture,  it  has  by  no  means  sufficient  regularity 
and  completeness  to  accomplish  its  purpose  adequately  and  con- 
veniently. Rather,  it  is  just  as  unsystematic  as  the  events  in  the 
lives  of  single  peoples  have  been,  and  the  necessity  of  expressing 
the  endlessly  different  particulars  of  daily  life  has  only  allowed  it  to 
develop  so  that  the  correspondence  between  word  and  concept  is 
kept  rather  indefinite  and  changeable,  according  to  need  within 
somewhat  wide  limits.  Thus  all  work  in  those  sciences  which  must 
make  vital  use  of  these  means,  as  especially  psychology  and  sociology, 
or  philosophy  in  general,  is  made  extremely  difficult  by  the  ceaseless 
struggle  with  the  indefiniteness  and  ambiguity  of  language.  An 
improvement  of  this  condition  can  be  effected  only  by  introducing 
signs  in  place  of  words  for  the  representation  of  concepts,  as  the 
progress  of  science  allows  it,  and  equipping  these  signs  with  the 
manifold  which  from  experience  belongs  to  the  concept. 

An  intermediate  position  in  this  respect  is  taken  by  the  sciences 
which  were  indicated  above  as  parts  of  energetics.  In  this  realm 
there  is  added  to  the  concepts  order,  number,  size,  space,  and  time, 
a  new  concept,  that  of  energy,  which  finds  application  to  every 
single  phenomenon  in  this  whole  field,  just  as  do  those  more  general 
concepts.  This  is  due  to  the  fact  that  a  certain  quantity,  which 
is  known  to  us  most  familiarly  as  mechanical  work,  on  account  of 
its  qualitative  transformability  and  quantitative  constancy,  can 
be  shown  to  be  a  constituent  of  every  physical  phenomenon,  that 
is,  every  phenomenon  which  belongs  to  the  field  of  mechanics, 
physics,  and  chemistry.  In  other  words,  one  can  perfectly  character- 
ize every  physical  event  by  indicating  what  amounts  and  kinds  of 
energy  have  been  present  in  it  and  into  what  energies  they  have 
been  transformed.  Accordingly,  it  is  logical  to  designate  the  so- 
called  physical  phenomena  as  energetical. 

That  such  a  conception  is  possible  is  now  generally  admitted. 
On  the  other  hand,  its  expediency  is  frequently  questioned,  and  there 
is  at  present  so  much  the  more  reason  for  this  because  a  thorough 
presentation  of  the  physical  sciences  in  the  energetical  sense  has  not 
yet  been  made.  If  one  applies  to  this  question  the  criterion  of  the 
scientific  system  given  above,  the  completeness  of  the  correspondence 
between  the  representing  manifold  and  that  to  be  represented,  there 
is  no  doubt  that  all  previous  systematizations  in  the  form  of  hypo- 
theses which  have  been  tried  in  these  sciences  are  defective  in  this 
respect.  Formerly,  for  the  purpose  of  representing  experiences, 
manifolds  whose  character  corresponded  to  the  character  of  the 
manifold  to  be  represented  only  in  certain  salient  points  without 
consideration  of  any  rigid  agreement,  indeed,  even  without  definite 
question  as  to  such  an  agreement,  have  been  employed. 


ON  THE  THEORY   OF   SCIENCE  349 

The  energetical  conception  admits  of  that  definiteness  of  represen- 
tation which  the  condition  of  science  demands  and  renders  possible. 
For  each  special  manifold  character  of  the  field  a  special  kind  of 
energy  presents  itself:  science  has  long  distinguished  mechanical, 
electric,  thermal,  chemical,  etc.,  energies.  All  of  these  different 
kinds  hold  together  by  the  law  of  transformation  with  the  mainten- 
ance of  the  quantitative  amount,  and  in  so  far  are  united.  On  the 
other  hand,  it  has  been  possible  to  fix  upon  the  corresponding  ener- 
getical expression  for  every  empirically  discovered  manifold.  As  a 
future  system  of  united  energetics,  we  have  then  a  table  of  possible 
manifolds  of  which  energy  is  capable.  In  this  we  must  keep  in  mind 
the  fact  that,  in  accordance  with  the  law  of  the  conservation,  energy 
is  a  necessarily  positive  quantity  which  also  is  furnished  with  the 
property  of  unlimited  possibility  of  addition;  therefore,  every  par- 
ticular kind  of  energy  must  have  this  character. 

The  very  small  manifold  which  seems  to  lack  this  condition  is 
much  widened  by  the  fact  that  every  kind  of  energy  can  be  separ- 
ated into  two  factors,  which  are  only  subject  to  the  limitation  that 
their  product,  the  energy,  fulfills  the  conditions  mentioned  while 
they  themselves  are  much  freer.  For  example,  one  factor  of  a  kind  of 
energy  can  become  negative  as  well  as  positive;  it  is  only  necessarj'- 
that  at  the  same  time  the  other  factor  should  become  negative, 
viz.,  positive. 

Thus  it  seems  possible  to  make  a  table  of  all  possible  forms  of 
energy,  by  attributing  all  thinkable  manifold  characteristics  to  the 
factors  of  the  energy  and  then  combining  them  by  pairs  and  cutting 
out  those  products  which  do  not  fulfill  the  above-mentioned  con- 
ditions. For  a  number  of  years  I  have  tried  from  time  to  time  to 
carry  out  this  programme,  but  I  have  not  yet  got  far  enough  to 
justify  publication  of  the  results  obtained. 

If  we  turn  to  the  biological  sciences,  in  them  the  phenomenon  of  life 
appears  to  us  as  new.  If  we  stick  to  the  observed  facts,  keeping  our-- 
selves  free  from  aU  hypotheses,  we  observe  as  the  general  characteris- 
tics of  the  phenomena  of  life  the  continuous  stream  of  energy  which 
courses  through  a  relatively  constant  structure.  Change  of  substance 
is  only  a  part,  although  a  very  important  part,  of  this  stream.  Espe- 
cially in  plants  we  can  observe  at  first  hand  the  great  importance  of 
energy  in  its  most  incorporeal  form,  the  sun's  rays.  Along  with  this, 
self-preservation  and  development  and  reproduction,  the  begetting 
of  offspring  of  like  nature,  are  characteristic.  All  of  these  properties 
must  be  present  in  order  that  an  organism  may  come  into  existence ; 
they  must  also  be  present  if  the  reflecting  man  is  to  be  able  by 
repeated  experience  to  form  a  concept  of  any  definite  organism, 
whether  of  a  lion  or  of  a  mushroom.  Other  organisms  are  met  with 
which  do  not  fulfill  these  conditions;  on  account  of  their  rarity,  how- 


350  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

ever,  they  do  not  lead  to  a  species  concept,  but  are  excluded  from 
scientific  consideration  (except  for  special  purposes)  as  deformities  or 
monsters. 

While  organisms  usually  work  with  kinds  of  energy  which  we  know 
well  from  the  inorganic  world,  organs  are  found  in  the  higher  forms 
which  without  doubt  cause  or  assist  transfers  of  energy,  but  we 
cannot  yet  say  definitely  what  particular  kind  of  energy  is  active  in 
them.  These  organs  are  called  nerves,  and  their  function  is  regularly 
that,  after  certain  forms  of  energy  have  acted  upon  one  end  of  them, 
they  should  act  at  the  other  end  and  release  the  energies  stored  up 
there  which  then  act  in  their  special  manner.  That  energetical 
transformations  also  take  place  in  the  nerve  during  the  process  of 
nervous  transmission  can  be  looked  upon  as  demonstrated.  We 
shall  thus  be  justified  in  speaking  of  a  nerve  energy,  while  leaving  it 
undecided  whether  there  is  here  an  energy  of  a  particular  kind,  or 
perhaps  chemical  energy,  or  finally  a  combination  of  several  energies. 

While  these  processes  can  be  shown  objectively  by  the  stimulation 
of  the  nerve  and  its  corresponding  releasing  reaction  in  the  end 
apparatus  (for  instance,  a  muscle),  we  find  in  ourselves,  connected 
with  certain  nervous  processes,  a  phenomenon  of  a  new  sort  which 
we  call  self-consciousness.  From  the  agreement  of  our  reactions 
with  those  of  other  people  we  conclude  with  scientific  probability 
that  they  also  have  self-consciousness;  and  we  are  justified  in  making 
the  same  conclusion  with  regard  to  some  higher  animals.  How  far 
down  something  similar  to  this  is  present  cannot  be  determined  by 
the  means  at  hand,  since  the  analogy  of  organization  and  of  behavior 
diminishes  very  quickly;  but  the  line  is  probably  not  very  long,  in 
view  of  the  great  leap  from  man  to  animal.  Moreover,  there  are  many 
reasons  for  the  view  that  the  gray  cortical  substance  in  the  brain, 
with  its  characteristic  pyramidal  cell,  is  the  anatomical  substratum 
of  this  kind  of  nervous  activity. 

The  study  of  the  processes  of  self-consciousness  constitutes  the  chief 
task  of  psychology.  To  this  science  belong  those  fields  which  are  gener- 
ally allotted  to  philosophy,  especially  logic  and  epistemology,  while  aes- 
thetics, and  still  more  ethics,  are  to  be  reckoned  with  the  social  sciences. 

The  latter  have  to  do  with  living  beings  in  so  far  as  they  can  be 
united  in  groups  with  common  functions.  Here  in  place  of  the  indi- 
vidual mind  appears  a  collective  mind,  which  owing  to  the  adjust- 
ment of  the  differences  of  the  members  of  society  shows  simpler 
conditions  than  that.  From  this  comes  especially  the  task  of  the 
historical  sciences.  The  happenings  in  the  world  accessible  to  us  are 
conditioned  partly  by  physical,  partly  by  psychological  factors,  and 
both  show  a  temporal'  mutability  in  one  direction.  Thus  arises  on 
the  one  hand  a  history  of  heaven  and  earth,  on  the  other  hand  a 
history  of  organisms  up  to  man. 


ON   THE   THEORY   OF   SCIENCE  351 

All  history  has  primarily  the  task  of  fixing  past  events  through  the 
effects  which  have  remained  from  them.  Where  such  are  not  access- 
ible, only  analogy  is  left,  a  very  doubtful  means  for  gaining  a  concep- 
tion of  those  events.  But  it  must  be  kept  in  mind  that  an  event  which 
has  left  no  evident  traces  has  no  sort  of  interest  for  us,  for  our  interest 
is  directly  proportional  to  the  amount  of  change  which  that  event  has 
caused  in  what  we  have  before  us.  The  task  of  historical  science  is 
just  as  little  exhausted,  however,  with  the  fixing  of  former  events 
as,  for  instance,  the  task  of  physics  with  the  establishment  of  a  single 
fact,  as  the  temperature  of  a  given  place  at  a  given  time.  Rather  the 
individual  facts  must  serve  to  bring  out  the  general  characteristics  of 
the  collective  mind,  and  the  much-discussed  historical  laws  are  laws 
of  collective  psychology.  Just  as  physical  and  chemical  laws  are 
deduced  in  order  with  their  help  to  predict  the  course  of  future  phys- 
ical events  (to  be  called  forth  either  experimentally  or  technically),  so 
should  the  historical  laws  contribute  to  the  formation  and  control  of 
social  and  political  development.  We  see  that  the  great  statesmen  of 
all  time  have  eagerly  studied  history  for  this  purpose,  and  from  that 
we  derive  the  assurance  that  there  are  historical  laws  in  spite  of  the 
objections  of  numerous  scholars. 

After  this  brief  survey,  if  we  look  back  over  the  road  we  have  come, 
we  observe  the  following  general  facts.  In  every  case  the  development 
of  a  science  consists  in  the  formation  of  concepts  by  certain  abstrac- 
tions from  experience,  and  setting  of  these  concepts  in  relation  with 
each  other  so  that  a  systematical  control  of  certain  sides  of  our 
experience  is  made  possible.  These  relations,  according  to  their  gener- 
ality and  reliability,  are  called  rules  or  laws.  A  law  is  the  more 
important  the  more  it  definitely  expresses  concerning  the  greatest 
possible  number  of  things,  and  the  more  accurately,  therefore,  it  en- 
ables us  to  predict  the  future.  Every  law  rests  upon  an  incomplete  in- 
duction, and  is  therefore  subject  to  modification  by  experience.  From 
this  there  results  a  double  process  in  the  development  of  science. 

First,  the  actual  conditions  are  investigated  to  find  out  whether,  be- 
sides those  already  known,  new  rules  or  laws,  that  is,  constant  relations 
between  individual  peculiarities,  cannot  be  discovered  between  them. 
This  is  the  inductive  process,  and  the  induction  is  always  an  incom- 
plete one  on  account  of  the  limitlessness  of  all  possible  experience. 

Immediately  the  relationship  found  inductively  is  applied  to  cases 
which  have  not  yet  been  investigated.  Especially  such  cases  are 
investigated  as  result  from  a  combination  of  several  inductive  laws. 
If  these  are  perfectly  'certain,  and  the  combination  is  also  properly 
made,  the  result  has  claim  to  unconditional  validity.  This  is  the 
lim-it  which  all  sciences  are  striving  to  reach.  It  has  almost  been 
reached  in  the  simpler  sciences :  in  mathematics  and  in  certain  parts 
of  mechanics.   This  is  called  the  deductive  process. 


352  METHODOLOGY  OF  SCIENCE 

In  the  actual  working  of  every  science  the  two  methods  of  investiga- 
tion are  continually  changing.  The  best  means  of  finding  new  success- 
ful inductions  is  in  the  making  of  a  deduction  on  a  very  insufficient 
basis,  perhaps,  and  subsequently  testing  it  in  experience.  Sometimes 
the  elements  of  his  deductions  do  not  come  into  the  investigator's 
consciousness;  in  such  cases  we  speak  of  scientific  instinct.  On  the 
other  hand  we  have  much  evidence  from  great  mathematicians  that 
they  were  accustomed  to  find  their  general  laws  by  the  method  of 
induction,  by  trying  and  considering  single  cases;  and  that  the 
deductive  derivation  from  other  known  laws  is  an  independent 
operation  which  sometimes  does  not  succeed  until  much  later.  Indeed 
there  is  to-day  a  number  of  mathematical  propositions  which  have 
not  yet  reached  the  second  stage  and  therefore  have  at  present  a 
purely  inductive  empirical  character.  The  proportion  of  such  laws  in 
science  increases  very  quickly  with  the  rise  in  the  scale  (page  339). 

Another  peculiarity  which  may  be  mentioned  here  is  that  in  the 
scale  all  previous  sciences  have  the  character  of  applied  sciences 
(page  341)  with  reference  to  those  which  follow,  since  they  are  every- 
where necessary  in  the  technique  of  the  latter,  yet  do  not  serve  to 
increase  their  own  field  but  are  merely  auxiliaries  to  the  latter. 

If  we  ask  finally  what  influence  upon  the  shaping  of  the  future  such 
investigations  as  those  which  have  been  sketched  in  outline  above 
can  have,  the  following  can  be  said.  Up  till  now  it  has  been  considered 
a  completely  uncontrollable  event  whether  and  where  a  great  and 
influential  man  of  science  has  developed.  It  is  obvious  that  such  a 
man  is  among  the  most  costly  treasures  which  a  people  (and,  indeed, 
humanity)  can  possess.  The  conscious  and  regular  breeding  of  such 
rarities  has  not  been  considered  possible.  While  this  is  still  the  case 
for  the  very  exceptional  genius,  we  see  in  the  countries  of  the  older 
civilization,  especially  in  Germany  at  present,  a  system  of  education 
in  vogue  in  the  universities  by  which  a  regular  harvest  of  young 
scientific  men  is  gained  who  not  only  have  a  mastery  of  knowledge 
handed  down,  but  also  of  the  technique  of  discovery.  Thereby  the 
growth  of  science  is  made  certain  and  regular,  and  its  pursuit  is 
raised  to  a  higher  plane.  These  results  were  formerly  attained  chiefly 
by  empirically  and  oftentimes  by  accidental  processes.  It  is  a  task  of 
scientific  theory  to  make  this  activity  also  regular  and  systematic,  so 
that  success  is  no  more  dependent  solely  upon  a  special  capacity  for 
the  founding  of  a  "school"  but  can  also  be  attained  by  less  original 
minds.  By  the  mastery  of  methods  the  way  to  considerably  higher 
performances  than  he  could  otherwise  attain  will  be  open  for  the 
exceptionally  gifted. 


THE   CONTENT   AND    VALIDITY    OF    THE   CAUSAL   LAW 

BY    BENNO    ERDMANN 

(Translated  from  the  German  by  Professor  Walter  T.  Marvin,  Western  Reserve 

University) 

[Benno  Erdmann,  Professor  of  Philosophy,  University  of  Bonn,  since  1898. 
b. October  5,  1851,  Glogau  in  Schlesien,  Germany.  Ph.D.;  Privy  Councilor. 
Academical  Lecturer,  Berlin,  1876-  ;  Special  Professor,  Kiel,  1878-79; 
Regular  Prof essor,  i6iU  1879-84;  ibid.  Breslau,  1884-90;  ibid.  Halle,  1890- 
98.  Member  various  scientific  and  learned  societies.  Author  of  The  Axioms 
of  Geometry;  Kant's  Criticism;  Logic;  Psychological  Researches  on  Reading 
(together  with  Prof.  Ramon  Dodge) ;  The  Psychology  of  the  Child  and  the 
School;  Historical  Researches  on  Kant's  Prolegomena,  and  many  other  works 
and  papers  in  Philosophy.] 

We  have  learned  to  regard  the  real,  which  we  endeavor  to  appre- 
hend scientifically  in  universally  valid  judgments,  as  a  whole  that  is 
connected  continuously  in  time  and  in  space  and  by  causation,  and 
that  is  accordingly  continuously  self-evolving.  This  continuity  of 
connection  has  the  following  result,  namely,  every  attempt  to  classify 
•the  sum  total  of  the  sciences  on  the  basis  of  the  difference  of  their 
objects  leads  merely  to  representative  types,  that  is,  to  species  which 
glide  into  one  another.  We  find  no  gaps  by  means  of  which  we  can 
separate  sharply  physics  and  chemistry,  botany  and  zoology,  political 
and  economic  history  and  the  histories  of  art  and  religion,  or,  again, 
history,  philology,  and  the  study  of  the  prehistoric. 

As  are  the  objects,  so  also  are  the  methods  of  science.  They  are 
separable  one  from  another  only  through  a  division  into  represent- 
ative types;  for  the  variety  of  these  methods  is  dependent  upon  the 
variety  of  the  objects  of  our  knowledge,  and  is,  at  the  same  time, 
determined  by  the  difference  between  the  manifold  forms  of  our 
thought,  itself  a  part  of  the  real,  with  its  elements  also  gliding  into 
one  another.^ 

The  threads  which  join  the  general  methodology  of  scientific 
thought  with  neighboring  fields  of  knowledge  run  in  two  main  direc- 
tions. In  the  one  direction  they  make  up  a  closely  packed  cable, 
whereas  in  the  other  their  course  diverges  into  all  the  dimensions 
of  scientific  thought.  That  is  to  say,  first,  methodology  has  its  roots 
in  logic,  in  the  narrower  sense,  namely,  in  the  science  of  the  element- 
ary forms  of  our  thought  which  enter  into  the  make-up  of  all  scien- 
tific methods.  .Secondly,  methodology  has  its  source  in  the  methods 
themselves  which  actually,  and  therefore  technically,  develop  in  the 

^  Cf.  the  author's  "Theorie  der  Typeneinteilungen,"  Phihsophische  Monat- 
shefte,  vol.  xxx,  Berlin,  1894. 


354  METHODOLOGY  OF  SCIENCE 

various  fields  of  our  knowledge  out  of  the  problems  peculiar  to  those 
fields. 

It  is  the  office  of  scientific  thought  to  interpret  validly  the  objects 
that  are  presented  to  us  in  outer  and  inner  perception,  and  that 
can  be  derived  from  both  these  sources.  We  accomplish  this  inter- 
pretation entirely  through  judgments  and  combinations  of  judgments 
of  manifold  sorts.  The  concepts,  which  the  older  logic  regarded  as 
the  true  elementary  forms  of  our  thinking,  are  only  certain  selected 
types  of  judgment,  such  stereotyped  judgments  as  those  which 
make  up  definitions  and  classifications,  and  which  appear  independ- 
ent and  fundamental  because  their  subject-matter,  that  is,  their 
intension  or  extension,  is  connected  through  the  act  of  naming  with 
certain  words.  Scientific  methods,  then,  are  the  ways  and  means 
by  which  our  thought  can  accomplish  and  set  forth,  in  accordance 
with  its  ideal,  this  universally  valid  interpretation. 

There  belongs,  accordingly,  to  methodology  a  list  of  problems 
which  we  can  divide,  to  be  sure  only  in  abstracto,  into  three  separ- 
ate groups.  First,  methodology  has  to  analyze  the  methods  which 
have  been  technically  developed  in  the  different  fields  of  knowledge 
into  the  elementary  forms  of  our  thinking  from  which  they  have 
been  built  up.  Next  to  this  work  of  analyzing,  there  comes  a  second 
task  which  may  be  called  a  normative  one;  for  it  follows  that  we' 
must  set  forth  and  deduce  systematically  from  their  sources  the 
nature  of  these  manifold  elements,  their  resulting  connection,  and 
their  vahdity.  To  these  two  offices  must  be  added  a  third  that  we 
may  call  a  potiori  a  synthetic  one ;  for  finally  we  must  reconstruct  out 
of  the  elements  of  our  thinking,  as  revealed  by  analysis,  the  methods 
belonging  to  the  different  fields  of  knowledge  and  also  determine 
their  different  scope  and  validity. 

The  beginning  of  another  conception  of  the  office  of  methodology 
can  be  found  in  those  thoughts  which  have  become  significant, 
especially  in  Leibnitz's  fragments  and  drafts  of  a  calculus  ratiocinator 
or  a  specieuse  generate.  The  foregoing  discussion  has  set  aside  all 
hope  that  these  beginnings  and  their  recent  development  may  give, 
of  the  possibility  of  constructing  the  manifold  possible  methods  a 
priori,  that  is,  before  or  independent  of  experience.  However,  it 
remains  entirely  undecided,  as  it  should  in  this  our  preliminary 
account  of  the  office  of  general  methodology,  whether  or  not  all 
methods  of  our  scientific  thought  will  prove  to  be  ultimately  but 
branches  of  one  and  the  same  universal  method,  a  thought  contained 
in  the  undertakings  just  referred  to.  Although  modern  empiricism, 
affiliated  as  it  is  with  natural  science,  tends  to  answer  this  question 
in  the  affirmative  even  more  definitely  and  dogmatically  than  any 
type  of  the  older  rationalism,  still  the  question  is  one  that  can  be 
decided  only  in  the  course  of  methodological  research. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW     355 

The  conception  of  a  methodology  of  scientific  thought  can  be 
said  to  be  almost  as  old  as  scientific  thought  itself;  for  it  is  already 
contained  essentially,  though  undifferentiated,  in  the  Socratic 
challenge  of  knowledge.  None  the  less,  the  history  of  methodology, 
as  the  history  of  every  other  science,  went  through  the  course  of 
which  Kant  has  given  a  classical  description.  "  No  one  attempts 
to  construct  a  science  unless  he  can  base  it  on  some  idea;  but  in  the 
elaboration  of  it  the  schema,  nay,  even  the  definition  which  he  gives 
in  the  beginning  of  his  science,  corresponds  very  seldom  to  his  idea, 
which,  like  a  germ,  lies  hidden  in  the  reason,  and  all  the  parts  of 
which  are  still  enveloped  and  hardly  distinguishable  even  under 
microscopical  observation."  ^ 

We  are  indebted  to  the  Greek,  and  especially  to  the  Platonic- 
Aristotelian  philosophy  for  important  contributions  to  the  under- 
standing of  the  deductive  method  of  mathematical  thought.  It 
was  precisely  this  trend  of  philosophic  endeavor  which,  though 
furnishing  for  the  most  part  the  foundation  of  methodological 
doctrine  well  on  into  the  seventeenth  century,  offered  no  means 
of  differentiating  the  methods  that  are  authoritative  for  our  know- 
ledge of  facts.  What  Socrates  was  perhaps  the  first  to  call  "induc- 
tion," is  essentially  different,  as  regards  its  source  and  aim,  from  the 
inductive  methods  that  direct  our  research  in  natural  and  mental 
science.  For  it  is  into  these  two  fields  that  we  have  to  divide  the 
totality  of  the  sciences  of  facts,  the  material  sciences,  let  us  call 
them,  in  opposition  to  the  formal  or  mathematical  sciences,  - —  that 
is,  if  we  are  to  do  justice  to  the  difference  between  sense  and  self- 
perception,  or  "outer"  and  "inner"  perception. 

Two  closely  connected  forces  especially  led  astray  the  methodo- 
logical opinions  regarding  the  material  sciences  till  the  end  of  the 
eighteenth  century,  and  in  part  until  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth 
century.  We  refer,  in  the  first  place,  to  that  direction  of  thought 
which  gives  us  the  right  to  characterize  the  Platonic-Aristotelian 
philosophy  as  a  '' concept  philosophy;"  namely,  the  circumstance 
that  Aristotelian  logic  caused  the  "concept"  to  be  set  before  the 
"judgment."  In  short,  we  refer  to  that  tendency  in  thought  which 
directs  the  attention  not  to  the  permanent  in  the  world's  occurrences, 
the  uniform  connections  of  events,  but  rather  to  the  seemingly  per- 
manent in  the  things,  their  essential  attributes  or  essences.  Thus 
the  concept  philosophy,  as  a  result  of  its  tendency  to  hypostasize, 
finds  in  the  abstract  general  concepts  of  things,  the  ideas,  the  eternal 
absolute  reality  that  constitutes  the  foundation  of  things  and  is 
contained  in  them  beside  the  accidental  and  changing  properties.^ 

1  Kant,  Kr.  d.  r.  Y .,  2d  ed.,  p.  862. 

^  According  to  Plato,  it  is  true,  the  ideas  are  separated  from  the  sensible  things; 
they  must  be  thought  in  a  conceptual  place,  for  the  space  of  sense-perception  is  to 


356  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

Here  we  have  at  once  the  second  force  which  inspired  the  ancient 
methodology.  These  ideas,  Hke  the  fundamentally  real,  constitute 
that  which  ultimately  alone  acts  in  all  the  coming  into  existence 
and  the  going  out  of  existence  of  the  manifold  things.  In  the  Aris- 
totelian theory  of  causation,  this  thought  is  made  a  principle;  and 
we  formulate  only  what  is  contained  in  it,  when  we  say  that,  accord- 
ing to  it,  the  efficient  and  at  the  same  time  final  causes  can  be 
deduced  through  mere  analysis  from  the  essential  content  of  the 
effects;  that,  in  fact,  the  possible  effects  of  every  cause  can  be  de- 
duced from  the  content  of  its  definition.  The  conceptual  determina- 
tion of  the  causal  relation,  and  with  it  in  principle  the  sum  total  of 
the  methods  in  the  material  sciences,  becomes  a  logical,  analytical, 
and  deductive  one.  These  sciences  remain  entirely  independent  of 
the  particular  content  of  experience  as  this  broadens,  and  so  do  also 
the  methods  under  discussion. 

As  a  consequence,  every  essential  difference  between  mathemat- 
ical thought  and  the  science  of  causes  is  done  away  with  in  favor 
of  a  rationalistic  construction  of  the  methods  of  material  science. 
Accordingly,  throughout  the  seventeenth  century,  the  ideal  of  all 
scientific  method  becomes,  not  the  inductive  method  that  founded 
the  new  epoch  of  the  science  of  to-day,  but  the  deductive  math- 
ematical method  applied  to  natural  scientific  research.  The  flourish 
of  trumpets  with  which  Francis  Bacon  hailed  the  onslaught  of  the 
inductive  methods  in  the  natural  science  of  the  time,  helped  in  no 
way;  for  he  failed  to  remodel  the  traditional,  Aristotelian-Scholastic 
conception  of  cause,  and,  accordingly,  failed  to  understand  both 
the  problem  of  induction  and  the  meaning  of  the  inductive  methods 
of  the  da3^^  Descartes,  Hobbes,  Spinoza,  and  related  thinkers 
develop  their  mathesis  universalis  after  the  pattern  of  geometrical 
thinking.  Leibnitz  tries  to  adapt  his  specieuse  generate  to  the  thought 
of  mathematical  analysis.  The  old  methodological  conviction  gains 
its  clear-cut  expression  in  Spinoza's  doctrine:  " Aliquid  efficitur  ah 
aliqua  re"  means  " aliquid  sequitur  ex  ejus  definitione." 

The  logically  straight  path  is  seldom  the  one  taken  in  the  course 
of  the  history  of  thought.  The  new  formulation  and  solution  of 
problems  influence  us  first  through  their  evident  significance  and 
consequences,  not  through  the  traditional  presuppositions  upon 
which  they  are  founded.  Thus,  in  the  middle  of  the  seventeenth 
century,  when  insight  into  the  precise  difference  between  mental 
and  physical  events  gave  rise  to  pressing  need  for  its  definite  formu- 
lation, no  question  arose  concerning  the  dogmatic  presupposition 

be  understood  as  non-being,  matter.  The  things  revealed  to  sense,  however, 
occupy  a  middle  position  between  being  and  non-being,  so  that  they  partake  of 
the  idpas.  In  this  sense,  the  statement  made  above  holds  also  of  the  older  view 
of  the  concept  philosophy. 

'■  Cf.  the  articles  on  Francis  Bacon  by  Chr.  Sigwart  in  the  Preussische  Jahr- 
hiXcher,  xii,  1863,  and  xiii,  1864. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF   THE  CAUSAL  LAW     357 

of  a  purely  logical  (analytisch)  relationship  between  cause  and  effect; 
but,  on  the  contrary,  this  presupposition  was  then  for  the  first  time 
brought  clearly  before  consciousness.  It  was  necessary  to  take  the 
roundabout  way  through  occasionalism  and  the  preestablished 
harmony,  including  the  latter 's  retreat  to  the  omnipotence  of  God, 
before  it  was  possible  to  raise  the  question  of  the  validity  of  the 
presupposition  that  the  connection  between  cause  and  effect  is 
analytic  and  rational. 

Among  the  leading  thinkers  of  the  period  this  problem  was  re- 
cognized as  the  cardinal  problem  of  contemporaneous  philosophy.  It 
is  further  evidence  how  thoroughly  established  this  problem  must 
have  been  among  the  more  deeply  conceived  problems  of  the  time 
in  the  middle  of  the  eighteenth  century,  that  Hume  and  Kant  were 
forced  to  face  it,  led  on,  seemingly  independently  of  each  other, 
and  surely  from  quite  different  presuppositions  and  along  entirely 
different  ways.  The  historical  evolution  of  that  which  from  the 
beginning  has  seemed  to  philosophy  the  solving  of  her  true  problem 
has  come  to  pass  in  a  way  not  essentially  different  from  that  of  the 
historical  evolution  in  all  other  departments  of  human  knowledge. 
Thus,  in  the  last  third  of  the  seventeenth  century,  Newton  and 
Leibnitz  succeeded  in  setting  forth  the  elements  of  the  infinitesimal 
calculus;  and,  in  the  fifth  decade  of  the  nineteenth  century,  Robert 
Mayer,  Helmholtz,  and  perhaps  Joule,  formulated  the  law  of  the 
conservation  of  energy.  In  one  essential  respect  Hume  and  Kant 
are  agreed  in  the  solution  of  the  new,  and  hence  contemporaneously 
misunderstood,  problem.  Both  realized  that  the  connection  be- 
tween the  various  causes  and  effects  is  not  a  rational  analytic,  but 
an  empirical  synthetic  one.  However,  the  difference  in  their  presup- 
positions as  well  as  method  caused  this  common  result  to  make  its 
appearance  in  very  different  light  and  surroundings.  In  Hume's 
empiricism  the  connection  between  cause  and  effect  appears  as  the 
mere  empirical  result  of  association;  whereas  in  Kant's  rationalism 
this  general  relation  between  cause  and  effect  becomes  the  funda- 
mental condition  of  all  possible  experience,  and  is,  as  a  conse- 
quence, independent  of  all  experience.  It  rests,  as  a  means  of 
connecting  our  ideas,  upon  an  inborn  uniformity  of  our  thought. 

Thus  the  way  was  opened  for  a  fundamental  separation  of  the 
inductive  material  scientific  from  the  deductive  mathematical 
method.  For  Hume  mathematics  becomes  the  science  of  the  rela- 
tions of  ideas,  as  opposed  to  the  sciences  of  facts.  For  Kant  philo- 
sophical knowledge  is  the  knowledge  of  the  reason  arising  from 
concepts,  whereas  the  mathematical  is  that  arising  from  the  con- 
struction of  concepts.  The  former,  therefore,  studies  the  particular 
only  in  the  universal;  the  latter,  the  universal  in  the  particular, 
nay,  rather  in  the  individual. 


358  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

Both  solutions  of  the  new  problem  which  in  the  eighteenth  cen- 
tury supplant  the  old  and  seemingly  self-evident  presupposition, 
appear  accordingly  embedded  in  the  opposition  between  the  ration- 
alistic and  empiristic  interpretation  of  the  origin  and  validity  of  our 
knowledge,  the  same  opposition  that  from  antiquity  runs  through 
the  historical  development  of  philosophy  in  ever  new  digressions. 

Even  to-day  the  question  regarding  the  meaning  and  the  validity 
of  the  causal  connection  stands  between  these  contrary  directions 
of  epistemological  research;  and  the  ways  leading  to  its  answer 
separate  more  sharply  than  ever  before.  It  is  therefore  more  press- 
ing in  our  day  than  it  was  in  earlier  times  to  find  a  basis  upon  which 
we  may  build  further  epistemologicallj'^  and  therefore  methodologic- 
ally. The  purpose  of  the  present  paper  is  to  seek  such  a  basis  for  the 
different  methods  employed  in  the  sciences  of  facts. 

As  has  already  been  said,  the  contents  of  our  consciousness,  which 
are  given  us  immediately  in  outer  and  inner  perception,  constitute 
the  raw  material  of  the  sciences  of  facts.  From  these  various  facts 
of  perception  we  derive  the  judgments  through  which  we  predict, 
guide,  and  shape  our  future  perception  in  the  course  of  possible 
experience.  These  judgments  exist  in  the  form  of  reproductive 
ideational  processes,  which,  if  logically  explicit,  become  inductive 
inferences  in  the  broader  sense.  These  inferences  may  be  said  to  be 
of  two  sorts,  though  fundamentally  only  two  sides  of  one  and  the 
same  process  of  thought;  they  are  in  part  analogical  inferences  and 
in  part  inductive  inferences  in  the  narrower  sense.  The  former  infers 
from  the  particular  in  a  present  perception,  which  in  previous  per- 
ceptions was  uniformly  connected  with  other  particular  contents  of 
perception,  to  a  particular  that  resembles  those  other  contents  of  per- 
ception. In  short,  they  are  inferences  from  a  particular  to  a  particular. 
After  the  manner  of  such  inferences  we  logically  formulate,  for 
example,  the  reproductive  processes,  whose  conclusions  run:  "This 
man  whom  I  see  before  me,  is  attentive,  feels  pain,  will  die;"  "this 
meteor  will  prove  to  have  a  chemical  composition  similar  to  known 
meteors,  and  also  to  have  corresponding  changes  on  its  surface  as 
the  result  of  its  rapid  passage  through  our  atmosphere."  The  induct- 
ive inferences  in  the  narrower  sense  argue,  on  the  contrary,  from 
the  perceptions  of  a  series  of  uniform  phenomena  to  a  universal, 
which  includes  the  given  and  likewise  all  possible  cases,  in  which 
a  member  of  the  particular  content  of  the  earlier  perceptions  is 
presupposed  as  given.  In  short,  they  are  conclusions  from  a  partic- 
ular to  a  universal  that  is  more  extensive  than  the  sum  of  the  given 
particulars.  For  example:  "All  men  have  minds,  will  die;"  "all 
meteoric  stones  will  prove  to  have  this  chemical  composition  and 
those  changes  of  surface." 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW     359 

There  is  no  controversy  regarding  the  inner  similarity  of  both 
these  types  of  inference  or  regarding  their  outward  structure;  or, 
again,  regarding  their  outward  difference  from  the  deductive  in- 
ferences, which  proceed  not  from  a  particular  to  a  particular  or 
general,  but  from  a  general  to  a  particular. 

There  is,  however,  difference  of  opinion  regarding  their  inner 
structure  and  their  inner  relation  to  the  deductive  inferences.  Both 
questions  depend  upon  the  decision  regarding  the  meaning  and 
validity  of  the  causal  relation.  The  contending  parties  are  recruited 
essentially  from  the  positions  of  traditional  empiricism  and  ration- 
alism and  from  their  modern  offshoots. 

We  maintain  first  of  all: 

L  The  presupposition  of  all  inductive  inferences,  from  now  on 
to  be  taken  in  their  more  general  sense,  is,  that  the  contents  of 
perception  are  given  to  us  uniformly  in  repeated  perceptions,  that  is, 
in  uniform  components  and  uniform  relations. 

2.  The  condition  of  the  validity  of  the  inductive  inferences  lies 
in  the  thoughts  that  the  same  causes  will  be  present  in  the  unobserved 
realities  as  in  the  observed  ones,  and  that  these  same  causes  ivill  bring 
forth  the  same  effects. 

3.  The  conclusions  of  all  inductive  inferences  have,  logically 
speaking,  purely  problematic  validity,  that  is,  their  contradictory 
opposite  remains  equally  thinkable.  They  are,  accurately  expressed, 
merely  hypotheses ,  whose  validity  needs  verification  through  future 
experience. 

The  first-mentioned  presupposition  of  inductive  inference  must  not 
be  misunderstood.  The  paradox  that  nothing  really  repeats  itself, 
that  each  stage  in  nature's  process  comes  but  once,  is  just  as  much 
and  just  as  little  justified  as  the  assertion,  everything  has  already 
existed.  It  does  not  deny  the  fact  that  we  can  discriminate  in  the 
contents  of  our  perceptions  the  uniformities  of  their  components 
and  relations,  in  short,  that  similar  elements  are  present  in  these 
ever  new  complexes.  This  fact  makes  it  possible  that  our  manifold 
perceptions  combine  to  make  up  one  continuous  experience.  Even 
our  paradox  presupposes  that  the  different  contents  of  our  percep- 
tions are  comparable  with  one  another,  and  reveal  accordingly 
some  sort  of  common  nature.  All  this  is  not  only  a  matter  of  course 
for  empiricism,  which  founds  the  whole  constitution  of  our  know- 
ledge upon  habits,  but  must  also  be  granted  by  every  rationalistic 
interpretation  of  the  structure  of  knowledge.  Every  one  that  is 
well  informed  know^  that  what  we  ordinarily  refer  to  as  facts  already 
includes  a  theory  regarding  them.  Kant  judges  in  this  matter  pre- 
cisely as  Hume  did  before  him  and  Stuart  Mill  after  him.  "  If  cin- 
nabar were  sometimes  red  and  sometimes  black,  sometimes  light  and 
sometimes  heavy,  if  a  man  could  be  changed  now  into  this,  now  into 


360  METHODOLOGY   OF   SCIENCE 

another  animal  shape,  if  on  the  longest  day  the  fields  were  some- 
times covered  with  fruit,  sometimes  with  ice  and  snow,  the  faculty 
of  my  empirical  imagination  would  never  be  in  a  position,  when 
representing  red  color,  to  think  of  heavy  cinnabar."  ^ 

The  assumption  that  in  recurring  perceptions  similar  elements 
of  content,  as  well  as  of  relation,  are  given,  is  a  necessary  condition 
of  the  possibility  of  experience  itself,  and  accordingly  of  all  those 
processes  of  thought  which  lead  us,  under  the  guidance  of  previous 
perceptions,  from  the  contents  of  one  given  perception  to  the  con- 
tents of  possible  perceptions. 

A  tradition  from  Hume  down  has  accustomed  us  to  associate  the 
relation  of  cause  and  effect  not  so  much  with  the  uniformity  of  co- 
existence as  with  the  uniformity  of  sequence.  Let  us  for  the  present 
keep  to  this  tradition.  Its  first  corollary  is  that  the  relation  of  cause 
and  effect  is  to  be  sought  in  the  uninterrupted  flow  and  connection 
of  events  and  changes.  The  cause  becomes  the  uniformly  preceding 
event,  the  constant  antecedens,  the  effect  the  uniformlj^  following,  the 
constant  consequens ,  in  the  course  of  the  changes  that  are  presented 
to  consciousness  as  a  result  of  foregoing  changes  in  our  sensorium. 

According  to  this  tradition  that  we  have  taken  as  our  point  of 
departure,  the  uniformity  of  the  sequence  of  events  is  a  necessary 
presupposition  of  the  relation  between  cause  and  effect.  This  uni- 
formity is  given  us  as  an  element  of  our  experience;  for  we  actually 
find  uniform  successions  in  the  course  of  the  changing  contents  of 
perception.  Further,  as  all  our  perceptions  are  in  the  first  instance 
sense-perceptions,  we  may  call  them  the  sensory  presupposition  of 
the  possibility  of  the  causal  relation. 

In  this  presupposition,  however,  there  is  much  more  involved  than 
the  name  just  chosen  would  indicate.  The  uniformity  of  sequence 
lies,  as  we  saw,  not  in  the  contents  of  perception  as  such,  which  are 
immediately  given  to  us.  It  arises  rather  through  the  fact  that,  in 
the  course  of  repeated  perceptions,  we  apprehend  through  abstraction 
.the  uniformities  of  their  temporal  relation.  Moreover,  there  lie  in  the 
repeated  perceptions  not  only  uniformities  of  sequence,  but  also 
uniformities  of  the  qualitative  content  of  the  successive  events 
themselves,  and  these  uniformities  also  must  be  apprehended  through 
abstraction.  Thus  these  uniform  contents  of  perception  make  up 
series  of  the  following  form: 

ai  ->  61 
tto  — >  bo 


1  Kant,  Kr.  d.  r.  V.,  1st  ed.,  pp.  100  f. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW    361 

The  presupposition  of  the  possibiUty  of  the  causal  relations  in- 
cludes, therefore,  more  than  mere  perceptive  elements.  It  involves 
the  relation  of  different,  if  you  will,  of  peculiar  contents  of  percep- 
tion, by  virtue  of  which  we  recognize  ac^—^h^  .  .  .  a,j  — >  h^  as  events 
that  resemble  one  another  and  the  event  a^  -^  h^  qualitatively  as  well 
as  in  their  sequence.  There  are  accordingly  involved  in  our  presup- 
position reproductive  elements  which  indicate  the  action  of  memory. 
In  order  that  I  may  in  the  act  of  perceiving  a^  —^  63  apprehend  the 
uniformity  of  this  present  content  with  that  of  Qo  -^  &2  ^^^  a^  ^  6j, 
these  earlier  perceptions  must  in  some  way,  perhaps  through  mem- 
ory,^ be  revived  with  the  present  perception. 

In  this  reproduction  there  is  still  a  further  element,  which  can 
be  separated,  to  be  sure  only  in  abstracto,  from  the  one  just  pointed 
out.  The  present  revived  content,  even  if  it  is  given  in  memory  as 
an  independent  mental  state,  is  essentially  different  from  the  original 
perception.  It  differs  in  all  the  modifications  in  which  the  memory 
of  lightning  and  thunder  could  differ  from  the  perception  of  their 
successive  occurrence,  or,  again,  the  memory  of  a  pain  and  the  re- 
sulting disturbance  of  attention  could  differ  from  the  corresponding 
original  experience.  However,  as  memory,  the  revived  experience 
presents  itself  as  a  picture  of  that  which  has  been  previously  per- 
ceived. Especially  is  this  the  case  in  memory  properly  so  called, 
where  the  peculiar  space  and  time  relations  individualize  the  revived 
experience.  If  we  give  to  this  identifying  element  in  the  associative 
process  a  logical  expression,  we  shall  have  to  say  that  there  is  in- 
volved in  revival,  and  especially  in  memory,  an  awareness  that  the 
present  ideas  recall  the  same  content  that  was  previously  given  us 
in  perception.  To  be  sure,  the  revival  of  the  content  of  previous 
perceptions  does  not  have  to  produce  ideas,  let  alone  memories. 
Rapid,  transitory,  or  habitual  revivals,  stimulated-  by  associative 
processes,  can  remain  unconscious,  that  is,  they  need  not  appear  as 
ideas  or  states  of  consciousness.  Stimulation  takes  place,  but  con- 
sciousness does  not  arise,  provided  we  mean  by  the  term  "  conscious- 
ness" the  genus  of  our  thoughts,  feelings,  and  volitions.  None  the 
less  it  must  not  be  forgotten  that  this  awareness  of  the  essential 
identity  of  the  present  revived  content  with  that  of  the  previous 
perception  can  be  brought  about  in  every  such  case  of  reproduction. 
How  all  this  takes  place  is  not  our  present  problem. 

We  can  apply  to  this  second  element  in  the  reproductive  process, 
which  we  have  found  to  be  essential  to  the  causal  relation,  a  Kantian 

'  It  is  not  our  present  concern  to  ascertain  how  this  actually  happens.  The 
psychological  presuppositions  of  the  present  paper  are  contained  in  the  theory  of 
reproduction  that  I  have  worked  out  in  connection  with  the  psychology  of  speech 
in  the  articles  on  "Die  psychologischen  Grundlagen  der  Beziehungen  zwischen 
Sprechen  und  Denken,"  Archiv  fiir  systematische  Philosophie,  11,  iii,  und  vii; 
cf.  note  1,  page  151. 


362  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

term,  "Recognition."  This  term,  however,  is  to  be  taken  only  in  the 
sense  called  for  by  the  foregoing  statements;  for  the  rationalistic 
presuppositions  and  consequences  which  mark  Kant's  "Synthesis 
of  Recognition  "  are  far  removed  from  the  present  line  of  thought. 

We  may,  then,  sum  up  our  results  as  follows:  In  the  presuppo- 
sition of  a  uniform  sequence  of  events,  which  we  have  accepted 
from  tradition  as  the  necessary  condition  of  the  possibility  of  the 
causal  relation,  there  lies  the  thought  that  the  contents  of  perception 
given  us  through  repeated  sense  stimulation  are  related  to  one 
another  through  a  reproductive  recognition. 

The  assumption  of  such  reproductive  recognition  is  not  justified 
merely  in  the  cases  so  far  considered.  It  is  already  necessary  in  the 
course  of  the  individual  perceptions  a  and  b,  and  hence  in  the  appre- 
hension of  an  occurrence.  It  makes  the  sequence  itself  in  which  a 
and  b  are  joined  possible;  for  in  order  to  apprehend  b  as  following 
upon  a,  in  case  the  perception  of  a  has  not  persisted  in  its  original 
form,  a  must  be  as  far  revived  and  recognized  upon  b's  entrance  into 
the  field  of  perception  as  it  has  itself  passed  out  of  that  field.  Other- 
wise, instead  of  b  following  upon  a  and  being  related  to  a,  there 
would  be  only  the  relationless  change  from  a  to  b.  This  holds  gen- 
erally and  not  merely  in  the  cases  where  the  perception  of  a  has 
disappeared  before  that  of  b  begins,  for  example,  in  the  case  of  light- 
ning and  thunder,  or  where  it  has  in  part  disappeared,  for  example, 
in  the  throwing  of  a  stone. 

We  have  represented  a  as  an  event  or  change,  in  order  that  uniform 
sequences  of  events  may  alone  come  into  consideration  as  the  pre- 
supposition of  the  causal  relation.  But  every  event  has  its  course  in 
time,  and  is  accordingly  divisible  into  many,  ultimately  into  infimtely 
many,  shorter  events.  Now  if  b  comes  only  an  infinitely  short  interval 
later  than  a,  and  by  hypothesis  it  must  come  later  than  a,  then  a 
corresponding  part  of  a  must  have  disappeared  by  the  time  b  appears. 
But  the  infinitesimal  part  of  a  perception  is  just  as  much  out  of  all 
consideration  as  would  be  an  infinitely  long  perception;  all  which  only 
goes  to  show  that  we  have  to  substitute  intervals  of  finite  length  in 
place  of  this  purely  conceptual  analysis  of  a  continuous  time  inter- 
val. This  leaves  the  foregoing  discussion  as  it  stands.  If  b  follows  a 
after  a  perceptible  finite  interval,  then  the  flow  or  development 
of  a  by  the  time  of  6's  appearance  must  have  covered  a  course  cor- 
responding to  that  interval;  and  all  this  is  true  even  though  the 
earlier  stages  of  a  remain  unchanged  throughout  the  interval  pre- 
ceding ?>'s  appearance.  The  present  instant  of  flow  is  distinct  from 
the  one  that  has  passed,  even  though  it  takes  place  in  precisely  the 
same  way.  The  former,  not  the  latter,  gives  the  basis  of  relation  which 
is  here  required,  and  therefore  the  former  must  be  reproduced  and 
recognized.    This  thought  also  is  included  in  the  foregoing  summary 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW    363 

of  what  critical  analysis  shows  to  be  involved  in  the  presupposition 
of  a  uniform  sequence. 

In  all  this  we  have  already  abandoned  the  field  of  mere  perception 
which  gave  us  the  point  of  departure  for  our  analysis  of  uniform 
sequence.  We  may  call  the  changing  course  of  perception  only  in  the 
narrower  meaning  the  sensory  presupposition  of  the  causal  relation. 
In  order  that  these  changing  contents  of  perception  may  be  known 
as  like  one  another,  as  following  one  another,  and  as  following  one 
another  uniformly,  they  must  be  related  to  one  another  through  a 
recognitive  reproduction. 

Our  critical  analysis  of  uniform  sequence  is,  however,  not  yet 
complete.  To  relate  to  one  another  the  contents  of  two  ideas  always 
requires  a  process  at  once  of  identifying  and  of  differentiating,  which 
makes  these  contents  members  of  the  relation,  and  which  accordingly 
presupposes  that  our  attention  has  been  directed  to  each  of  the  two 
members  as  weU  as  to  the  relation  itself  —  in  the  present  case,  to  the 
sequence.  Here  we  come  to  another  essential  point.  We  should  apply 
the  name  "thought"  to  every  ideational  process  in  which  attention 
is  directed  to  the  elements  of  the  mental  content  and  which  leads  us 
to  identify  with  one  another,  or  to  differentiate  from  one  another,  the 
members  of  this  content.^  The  act  of  relating,  which  knows  two 
events  as  similar,  as  following  one  another,  indeed,  as  following  one 
another  uniformly,  is  therefore  so  far  from  being  a  sensation  that  it 
must  be  claimed  to  be  an  act  of  thinking.  The  uniformity  of  sequence 
of  a  and  b  is  therefore  an  act  of  relating  on  the  part  of  our  thought, 
so  far  as  this  becomes  possible  solely  through  the  fact  that  we  at  one 
and  the  same  time  identify  with  one  another  and  differentiate  from 
one  another  a  as  cause  and  b  as  effect.  We  say  "  at  one  and  the  same 
time,"  because  the  terms  identifying  and  differentiating  are  corre- 
latives which  denote  two  different  and  opposing  sides  of  one  and  the 
same  ideational  process  viewed  logically.  Accordingly,  there  is  here 
no  need  of  emphasizing  that  the  act  of  relating,  which  enables  us  to 
think  a  as  cause  and  b  as  effect,  is  an  act  of  thought  also,  because  it 
presupposes  on  our  part  an  act  of  naming  which  raises  it  to  being 
a  component  of  our  formulated  and  discursive  thought.  We  therefore 
think  a  as  cause  and  b  as  effect  in  that  we  apprehend  the  former  as 
uniform  antecedens  and  the  latter  as  uniform  consequens. 

Have  we  not  the  right,  after  the  foregoing  analysis,  to  interpret 
the  uniform  sequence  of  events  solely  as  the  necessary  presupposi- 
tion of  the  causal  relation?  Is  it  not  at  the  same  time  the  adequate 
presupposition?  Yes,  is  it  not  the  causal  relation  itself?  As  we 
know,  empiricism  since  Hume  has  answered  the  last  question  in  the 

^  Cf.  the  author's  "Umrisse  zur  Psychologie  des  Denkens,"  in  Philosophische 
Abhandlungen  Chr.  Sigwart  .  .  .  gewidmet,  Tiibingen,  1900. 


364  METHODOLOGY   OF   SCIENCE 

affirmative,  and  rationalism  since  Kant  has  answered  it  in  the  nega- 
tive. 

We,  too,  have  seemingly  followed  in  our  discussion  the  course  of 
empiricism.  At  least,  I  find  nothing  in  that  discussion  which  a  con- 
sistent empiricist  might  not  be  willing  to  concede;  that  is,  if  he  is 
ready  to  set  aside  the  psychological  investigation  of  the  actual  pro- 
cesses which  we  here  presuppose  and  make  room  for  a  critical  anal3^sis 
of  the  content  of  the  relation  of  cause  and  effect.^    However,  the 

^  The  difference  between  the  two  pomts  of  view  can  be  made  clearer  by  an  illus- 
tration. The  case  that  we  shall  analyze  is  the  dread  of  coming  into  contact  Tvnth 
fire.  The  psychological  analysis  of  this  case  has  to  make  clear  the  mental  content 
of  the  dread  and  its  causes.  Such  dread  becomes  possible  only  when  we  are  aware 
of  the  burning  that  results  from  contact  with  fire.  We  could  have  learned  to  be 
aware  of  this  either  immediately  through  our  own  experience,  or  mediately 
through  the  communication  of  others'  experience.  In  both  cases  it  is  a  matter  of 
one  or  repeated  experiences.  In  all  cases  the  effects  of  earlier  experiences  equal 
association  and  recall,  which,  in  turn,  result  in  recognition.  The  recognition 
explaining  the  case  imder  discussion  arises  thus.  The  present  stimuli  of  visual 
perception  arouse  the  retained  impressions  of  previous  visual  perceptions  of  fire 
and  give  rise  to  the  present  perception  (apperception)  by  fusing  with  them.  By 
a  process  of  interweaving,  associations  are  joined  to  this  perception.  The  apper- 
ceptively  revived  elements  which  lie  at  the  basis  of  the  content  of  the  perception 
are  interwoven  by  association  with  memorj^  elements  that  retain  the  additional 
contents  of  previous  perceptions  of  fire,  viz.,  the  burning,  or,  again,  are  interwoven 
with  the  memory  elements  of  the  communications  regarding  such  burning.  By 
means  of  this  interweaving,  the  stimulation  of  the  apperceptive  element  transmits 
itself  to  the  remaining  elements  of  the  association  complex.  The  character  of  the 
association  is  different  under  different  conditions.  If  it  be  founded  only  upon  one 
experience,  then  there  can  arise  a  memory  or  a  recall,  in  the  wider  sense,  of  the 
foregoing  content  of  the  perception  and  feeling  at  the  tune  of  the  burning,  or, 
again,  there  can  arise  a  revival  wherein  the  stimulated  elements  of  retention  remain 
unconscious.  Again,  the  words  of  the  mother  tongue  that  denote  the  previous 
mental  content,  and  which  hkewise  belong  to  the  association  complex  (the  apper- 
ceiving  mass,  in  the  wider  sense),  can  be  excited  in  one  of  these  three  forms  and 
in  addition  as  abstract  verbal  ideas.  Each  one  of  these  forms  of  verbal  discharge 
can  lead  to  the  innervations  of  the  muscles  involved  in  speech,  which  bring  about 
some  sort  of  oral  expression  of  judgment.  Each  of  these  verbal  reproductions  can 
be  connected  with  each  of  the  foregoing  sensory  {sachlichen)  revivals.  Secondly, 
if  the  association  be  founded  upon  repeated  perceptions  on  the  part  of  the  person 
himself,  then  all  the  afore-mentioned  possibilities  of  reproduction  become  more 
complicated,  and,  in  addition,  the  mental  revivals  contain,  more  or  less,  only  the 
common  elements  of  the  previous  perceptions,  i.  e.,  reappear  in  the  form  of 
abstract  ideas  or  their  corresponding  unconscious  modifications.  In  the  third 
case  the  association  is  founded  upon  a  communication  of  others'  experience.  For 
the  sake  of  simplicity,  let  this  case  be  confined  to  the  following  instance.  The 
communication  consisted  in  the  assertion:  "AH  fire  will  burn  upon  contact." 
Moreover,  this  judgment  was  expressed  upon  occasion  of  imminent  danger  of 
burning.  There  can  then  arise,  as  is  perhaps  evident,  all  the  possibilities  men- 
tioned in  the  second  case,  only  that  here  there  will  be  a  stronger  tendency  toward 
verbal  reproduction  and  the  sensory  reproduction  will  be  less  fixed. 

In  the  first  two  cases  there  was  connected  with  the  perception  of  the  burning 
an  intense  feeling  of  pain.  In  the  third  the  idea  of  such  pain  added  itself  to  the 
visual  perception  of  the  moment.  The  associated  elements  of  the  earlier  mental 
contents  belong  likewise  to  the  apperceiving  mass  excited  at  the  moment,  in  fact 
to  that  part  of  it  excited  by  means  of  association  processes,  or,  as  we  can  again  say, 
depending  upon  the  point  from  which  we  take  our  view,  the  associative  or  apper- 
ceptive completion  of  the  content  of  present  perception.  If  these  pain  elements 
are  revived  as  memories,  i.  e.,  as  elements  in  consciousness,  they  give  rise  to  a  new 
disagreeable  feeling,  which  is  referred  to  the  possible  coming  sensation  of  burning. 
If  the  mental  modifications  corresponding  to  these  pain  elements  remain  uncon- 
scious, as  is  often  possible,  there  arises  none  the  less  the  same  result  as  regards  our 
feeling,  only  with  less  intensity.   This  feeling  tone  we  call  the  dread. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL   LAW    365 

decision  of  the  question,  whether  or  not  empiricism  can  determine 
exhaustively  the  content  that  we  think  in  the  causal  relation,  depends 
upon  other  considerations  than  those  which  we  have  until  now  been 
called  upon  to  undertake.  We  have  so  far  only  made  clear  what 
every  critical  analysis  of  the  causal  relation  has  to  concede  to  empiri- 
cism.  In  reality  the  empiristic  hypothesis  is  inadequate.   To  be  sure, 

As  a  result  of  the  sum  total  of  the  revivals  actual  and  possible,  there  is  finally 
produced,  according  to  the  particular  circumstances,  either  a  motor  reaction  or  an 
inhibitant  of  such  reaction.  Both  innervations  can  take  place  involimtarily  or 
voluntarily. 

The  critical  analysis  of  the  fact  that  we  dread  contact  with  fire,  even  has  another 
purpose  and  accordingly  proceeds  on  other  lines.  It  must  make  clear  under  what 
presuppositions  the  foresight  that  Ues  at  the  basis  of  such  dread  is  valid  for  future 
experience.  It  must  then  formulate  the  actual  process  of  revival  that  constitutes 
the  foundation  of  this  feeling  as  a  series  of  judgments,  from  which  the  meaning  and 
interconnection  of  the  several  judgments  will  become  clear.  Thus  the  critical 
analysis  must  give  a  logical  presentation  of  the  apperceptive  and  associative 
processes  of  revival. 

For  this  purpose  the  three  cases  of  the  psychological  analysis  reduce  themselves 
to  two:  viz.,  first,  to  the  case  in  which  an  immediate  experience  forms  the  basis, 
and  secondly,  to  that  in  which  a  variety  of  similar  mediately  or  immediately 
communicated  experiences  form  such  basis. 

In  the  first  of  these  logically  differentiated  cases,  the  transformation  into  the 
speech  of  formulated  thought  leads  to  the  following  inference  from  analogy : 

Fire  A  burned. 

Fire  B  is  similar  to  fire  A. 


Fire  B  -nail  burn. 

In  the  second  case  there  arises  a  syllogism  of  some  such  form  as: 

All  fire  causes  burning  upon  contact. 
This  present  phenomenon  is  fire. 

This  present  phenomenon  wiU  cause  burning  upon  contact. 

Both  premises  of  this  syllogism  are  inductive  inferences,  whose  implicit  meaning 
becomes  clear  when  we  formulate  as  follows : 

All  heretofore  investigated  instances  of  fire  have  burned,  therefore  all  fire 

bums. 
The  present  phenomenon  manifests  some  properties  of  fire,  wiU  consequently 

have  all  the  properties  thereof. 

The  present  phenomenon  will,  in  case  of  contact,  cause  burning. 

The  first  syllogism  goes  from  the  particular  to  the  particular.  The  second  proves 
itself  to  be  (contrary  to  the  analysis  of  Stuart  Mill)  an  inference  that  leads  from 
the  general  to  the  particular.  For  the  conclusion  is  the  particular  of  the  second 
parts  of  the  major  and  minor  premises;  and  these  second  parts  of  the  premises  are 
inferred  from  their  first  parts  in  the  two  possible  ways  of  inductive  inference.  The 
latter  do  not  contain  the  case  referred  to  in  the  conclusion,  but  set  forth  the  con- 
ditions of  carrying  a  result  of  previous  experience  over  to  a  new  case  with  inductive 
probability,  in  other  words,  the  conditions  of  making  past  experience  a  means  of 
foreseeing  future  experience.  It  would  be  superfluous  to  give  here  the  symbols 
of  the  two  forms  of  inductive  inference. 

We  remain  within  the  bounds  of  logical  analysis,  if  we  state  under  what  condi- 
tions conclusions  follow  necessarily  from  their  premises,  viz.,  the  conclusions 
of  arguments  from  analogy  and  of  syllogisms  in  the  narrower  sense,  as  well  as 
those  of  the  foregoing  inductive  arguments.  For  the  inference  from  analogy  and 
the  two  forms  of  inductive  inference,  these  conditions  are  the  presuppositions 
already  set  forth  in  the  text  of  the  present  paper,  that  in  the  as  yet  unobserved 
portion  of  reality  the  like  causes  will  be  found  and  they  will  give  rise  to  like  effects. 
For  the  syllogism  they  are  the  thought  that  the  predicate  of  a  predicate  is  the 
(mediate)  predicate  of  the  subject.  Only  the  further  analysis  of  these  presupposi- 
tions, which  is  undertaken  in  the  text,  leads  to  critical  considerations  in  the 
narrower  sense. 


366  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

the  proof  of  this  inadequacy  is  not  to  be  taken  from  the  obvious 
argument  which  Reid  raised  against  the  empiricism  of  Hume,  and 
which  compelled  Stuart  Mill  in  his  criticism  of  that  attack  ^  to  abandon 
his  empiristic  position  at  this  point.  No  doubt  the  conclusion  to  which 
we  also  have  come  for  the  time  being,  goes  much  too  far,  the  conclu- 
sion that  the  cause  is  nothing  but  the  uniform  antecedens  and  the 
effect  merely  the  uniform  consequens.  Were  it  true,  as  we  have 
hitherto  assumed,  that  every  uniformly  preceding  event  is  to  be 
regarded  as  cause  and  every  uniformly  following  event  as  effect,  then 
day  must  be  looked  upon  as  cause  of  night  and  night  as  cause  of  day. 

Empiricism  can,  however,  meet  this  objection  without  giving  up 
its  position;  in  fact,  it  can  employ  the  objection  as  an  argument  in  its 
favor;  for  this  objection  affects  only  the  manifestly  imperfect  formu- 
lation of  the  doctrine,  not  the  essential  arguments. 

It  should  have  been  pointed  out  again  and  again  in  the  foregoing 
exposition  that  only  in  the  first  indiscriminating  view  of  things  maj^ 
we  regard  the  events  given  us  in  perception  as  the  basis  of  our  concepts 
of  cause  and  effect.  All  these  events  are  intricately  mixed,  those  that 
are  given  in  self  perception  as  well  as  those  given  in  sense  perception. 
The  events  of  both  groups  flow  along  continuously.  Consequently, 
as  regards  time,  they  permit  a  division  into  parts,  which  division 
proceeds,  not  indeed  for  our  perception,  but  for  our  scientific  thought, 
in  short,  conceptually,  into  infinity.  The  events  of  sense  perception 
permit  also  conceptually  of  infinite  division  in  their  spatial  relations. 

It  is  sufficient  for  our  present  purpose,  if  we  turn  our  attention  to 
the  question  of  divisibility  in  time.  This  fact  of  divisibility  shows 
that  the  events  of  our  perception,  which  alone  we  have  until  now 
brought  under  consideration,  must  be  regarded  as  systems  of  events. 
We  are  therefore  called  upon  to  apportion  the  causal  relations  among 
the  members  of  these  systems.  Only  for  the  indiscriminating  view 
of  our  practical  Weltanschauung  is  the  perceived  event  a  the  cause 
of  the  perceived  event  h.  The  more  exact  analysis  of  our  theoretical 
apprehension  of  the  world  compels  us  to  dissect  the  events  a  and  h 
into  the  parts  a^,  a^,  a  ,  —  h^,  b^,  h  ,  and,  where  occasion  calls  for  it,  to 
continue  the  same  process  in  turn  for  these  and  further  components. 
We  have  accordingly  to  relate  those  parts  to  one  another  as  causes 
and  effects  which,  from  the  present  standpoint  of  analysis,  follow  one 
another  uniformly  and  immediately,  viz.,  follow  one  another  so  that 
from  this  standpoint  no  other  intervening  event  must  be  presupposed. 
In  this  way  we  come  to  have  a  well-ordered  experience.  The  disposi- 
tions to  such  experience  which  reveal  themselves  within  the  field  of 
practical  thought  taught  man  long  before  the  beginning  of  scientific 
methods  not  to  connect  causally  day  and  night  with  one  another,  but 
the  rising  and  setting  of  the  sun  with  day  and  night.  The  theoretical 

'  A  System  of  Logic,  Ratiocinative  and  Inductive,  bk.  in,  ch.  v,  §  6. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW    367 

analysis,  indeed,  goes  farther.  It  teaches  that  in  what  is  here  summed 
up  as  rising  of  the  sun  and  yonder  as  day,  there  he  again  intricate 
elements  requiring  special  attention,  in  our  own  day  extending  per- 
haps to  the  lines  of  thought  contained  in  the  electro-dynamic  theory 
of  light  and  of  electrons.  Still  the  ways  of  thought  remain  the  same 
on  all  the  levels  of  penetrating  analysis.  We  have  throughout  to  relate 
to  one  another  as  cause  and  effect  those  events  which,  in  a  well- 
ordered  experience,  must  be  regarded  as  following  one  another  imme- 
diately. The  cause  is  then  the  immediate  uniform  antecedens ,  the 
effect  the  immediate  uniform  consequens.  Otherwise  stated,  the  per- 
ceived events  that  we  are  accustomed,  from  the  standpoint  of  the 
practical  Weltanschauung,  to  regard  as  causes  and  effects,  e.  g.,  light- 
ning and  thunder,  from  the  theoretical  apprehension  of  the  world 
prove  to  be  infinitely  involved  collections  of  events,  whose  elements 
must  be  related  to  one  another  as  causes  and  effects  in  as  far  as  they 
can  be  regarded  as  following  one  another  immediately.  No  exception 
is  formed  by  expressions  of  our  rough  way  of  viewing  and  describing 
which  lead  us  without  hesitation  to  regard  as  cause  one  out  of  the  very 
many  causes  of  an  event,  and  this,  too,  not  necessarily  the  immedia>te 
uniformly  preceding  event.  All  this  lies  rather  in  the  nature  of  such 
a  hasty  view. 

The  present  limitation  of  uniform  sequence  to  cases  of  immediate 
sequence  sets  aside,  then,  the  objection  from  which  we  started,  in  that 
it  adopts  as  its  own  the  essential  point  in  question. 

Moreover,  the  way  that  leads  us  to  this  necessary  limitation  goes 
farther:  it  leads  to  a  strengthening  of  the  empiristic  position.  It 
brings  us  to  a  point  where  we  see  that  the  most  advanced  analysis 
of  intricate  systems  of  events  immediately  given  to  us  in  perception 
as  real  nowhere  reveals  more  than  the  simple  fact  of  uniform  sequence. 
Again  where  we  come  to  regard  the  intervals  between  the  events  that 
follow  one  another  immediately  as  very  short,  there  the  uniformity  of 
the  time  relation  makes,  it  would  seem,  the  events  for  us  merely 
causes  and  effects;  and  as  often  as  we  have  occasion  to  proceed  to 
the  smaller  time  differences  of  a  higher  order,  the  same  process  repeats 
itself;  for  we  dissect  the  events  that  make  up  our  point  of  departure 
into  ever  more  complex  systems  of  component  events,  and  the 
coarser  relations  of  uniform  sequence  into  ever  finer  immediate  ones. 
Nowhere,  seemingly,  do  we  get  beyond  the  field  of  events  in  uniform 
sequence,  which  finally  have  their  foundation  in  the  facts  of  perception 
from  which  they  are  drawn.  Thus  there  follows  from  this  conceptual 
refinement  of  the  point  of  departure  only  the  truth  that  nothing 
connects  the  events  as  causes  and  effects  except  the  immediate 
uniformity  of  sequence. 

None  the  less,  we  have  to  think  the  empiristic  doctrine  to  the  bot- 
tom, if  we  desire  to  determine  whether  or  not  the  hypothesis  which 


368  METHODOLOGY   OF  SCIENCE 

it  offers  is  really  sufficient  to  enable  us  to  deduce  the  causal  relation. 
For  this  purpose  let  us  remind  ourselves  that  the  question  at  issue 
is,  whether  or  not  this  relation  is  merely  a  temporal  connection  of 
events  that  are  given  to  us  in  perception  or  that  can  be  derived  from 
the  data  of  perception. 

Besides,  let  us  grant  that  this  relation  is  as  thoroughly  valid  for 
the  content  of  our  experience  as  empiricism  has  always,  and  ration- 
alism nearly  always,  maintained.  We  presuppose,  therefore,  as 
granted,  that  every  event  is  to  be  regarded  as  cause,  and  hence,  in 
the  opposite  time  relation,  as  effect,  mental  events  that  are  given 
to  us  in  self  perception  no  less  than  the  physical  whose  source  is  our 
sense  perception.  In  other  words,  we  assume  that  the  totality  of 
events  in  our  possible  experience  presents  a  closed  system  of  causal 
series,  that  is,  that  every  member  within  each  of  the  contemporary 
series  is  connected  with  the  subsequent  ones,  as  well  as  with  the 
subsequent  members  of  all  the  other  series,  backward  and  forward 
as  cause  and  effect;  and  therefore,  finally,  that  every  member  of 
every  series  stands  in  causal  relationship  with  every  member  of 
e'\iery  other  series.  We  do  not  then,  for  the  present  purpose,  burden 
ourselves  with  the  hypothesis  which  was  touched  upon  above,  that 
this  connection  is  to  be  thought  of  as  a  continuous  one,  namely,  that 
other  members  can  be  inserted  ad  infinitum  between  any  two  mem- 
bers of  the  series. 

We  maintain  at  the  same  time  that  there  is  no  justification  for 
separating  from  one  another  the  concepts,  causality  and  interaction. 
This  separation  is  only  to  be  justified  through  the  metaphysical 
hypothesis  that  reality  consists  in  a  multitude  of  independently 
existing  substances  inherently  subject  to  change,  and  that  their 
mutual  interconnection  is  conditioned  by  a  common  dependence 
upon  a  first  infinite  cause. ^  Every  connection  between  cause  and 
effect  is  mutual,  if  we  assume  with  Newton  that  to  every  action 
there  is  an  equal  opposing  reaction. 

In  that  we  bring  the  totality  of  knowable' reality,  as  far  as  it  is 
analyzable  into  events,  under  the  causal  relation,  we  may  regard 
the  statement  that  every  event  requires  us  to  seek  among  uniformly 
preceding  events  for  the  sufficient  causes  of  its  own  reality,  namely, 
the  general  causal  law,  as  the  principle  of  all  material  sciences.  For 
all  individual  instances  of  conformity  to  law  which  we  can  discover 
in  the  course  of  experience  are  from  this  point  of  view  only  special 
cases  of  the  general  universal  conformity  to  law  which  we  have  just 
formulated. 

^  This  doctrine  began  in  the  theological  evolution  of  the  Christian  concept  of 
God.  It  was  first  fundamentally  formulated  by  Leibnitz.  It  is  retained  in  Kant's 
doctrine  of  the  harmonia  generaUter  stabilita  and  the  latter's  consequences  for  the 
critical  doctrine  of  the  mundus  intelligibilis.  Hence  it  permeates  the  metaphysical 
doctrines  of  the  systems  of  the  nineteenth  century  in  various  ways. 


CONTENT  AND   VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL   LAW    369 

For  the  empiristic  interpretation,  the  (general)  causal  law  is  only 
the  highest  genus  of  the  individual  cases  of  empirically  synthetic 
relations  of  uniform  sequence.  Starting  from  these  presuppositions, 
it  cannot  be  other  than  a  generalization  from  experience,  that  is,  a 
carrying  over  of  observed  relations  of  uniform,  or,  as  we  may  now 
also  say,  constant  sequence  to  those  which  have  not  been  or  cannot 
be  objects  of  observation,  as  well  as  to  those  which  we  expect  to  ap- 
pear in  the  future.  Psychologically  regarded,  it  is  merely  the  most 
general  ex]3ression  of  an  expectation,  conditioned  through  associative 
reproduction,  of  uniform  sequence.  It  is,  therefore,  —  to  bring 
Hume's  doctrine  to  a  conclusion  that  the  father  of  modern  empiricism 
himself  did  not  draw,  —  a  species  of  temporal  contiguity. 

The  general  validity  which  we  ascribe  to  the  causal  law  is  ac- 
cordingly a  merely  empirical  one.  It  can  never  attain  apodeictic 
or  even  assertorical  validity,  but  purely  that  type  of  problematic 
validity  which  we  may  call  "real"  in  contradistinction  to  the  other 
type  of  problematic  validity  attained  in  judgments  of  objective  as 
well  as  of  subjective  and  hypothetical  possibility.^  No  possible  pro- 
gress of  experience  can  win  for  the  empiristically  interpreted  causal 
law  any  other  than  this  real  problematic  validity;  for  experience 
can  never  become  complete  a  parte  post,  nor  has  it  ever  been  com- 
plete a  parte  ante.  The  causal  law  is  valid  assertorically  only  in  so 
far  as  it  sums  up,  purely  in  the  way  of  an  inventory,  the  preceding 
experiences.  We  call  such  assumptions,  drawn  from  well-ordered 
experience  and  of  inductive  origin,  "hypotheses,"  whether  they  rest 
upon  generalizing  inductive  inferences  in  the  narrower  sense,  or  upon 
specializing  inferences  from  analogy.  They,  and  at  the  same  time 
the  empiristically  interpreted  causal  law,  are  not  hypotheses  in  the 
sense  in  which  Newton  rightly  rejected  all  formation  of  hypotheses,^ 
but  are  such  as  are  necessarily  part  of  all  methods  in  the  sciences  of 
facts  in  so  far  as  the  paths  of  research  lead  out  beyond  the  content 
given  immediately  in  perception  to  objects  of  only  possible  experience. 

The  assertion  of  Stuart  Mill,  in  opposition  to  this  conclusion, 
that  the  cause  must  be  thought  of  as  the  "invariable  antecedent" 
and,  correspondingly,  the  effect  as  the  "invariable  consequent,"^ 
does  all  honor  to  the  genius  of  the  thinker;  but  it  agrees  by  no  means 
with  the  empiristic  presuppositions  which  serve  as  the  basis  for  his 
conclusions.  For,  starting  from  these  presuppositions,  the  "invari- 
able sequence"  can  only  mean  one  that  is  uniform  and  constant 

1  Cf.  the  author's  Logik,  bd.  i,  §  61.        _ 

■^  "  Rationem  vero  harura  gravitatis  propriefcatum  ex  phaenomenis  nondum  potui 
deducere,  et  hypotheses  no'n  fingo.  Quicquid  enim  ex  phaenomenis  non  deducitur, 
hypothesis  vocanda  est ;  et  hypotheses  seu  metaphysicae,  seu  physicae,  seu  qualita- 
tum  occultarum,  seu  mechanicae,  in  philosophia  experimentah  locum  non  habent. 
In  hac  philosophia  propositiones  deducuntur  ex  phaenomenis,  et  redduntur  gener- 
ales  per  indudionem."   Newton,  at  the  end  of  his  chief  work. 

^  Logic,  bk.  iii,  ch.  v,  §  2. 


370  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

according  to  past  experience,  and  that  we  henceforth  carry  over 
to  not  yet  observed  events  as  far  as  these  prove  in  conformity  with 
it,  and  in  this  way  verify  the  anticipation  contained  in  our  general 
assertion.  The  same  holds  of  the  assertion  through  which  Mill  en- 
deavors to  meet  the  above-mentioned  objection  of  E,eid,  namely,  that 
the  unchanging  sequence  must  at  the  same  time  be  demonstrably 
an  "  unconditional "  one.  The  language  in  which  experience  speaks  to 
us  knows  the  term  "the  unconditioned"  as  little  as  the  term  "the 
unchangeable,"  even  though  this  have,  as  Mill  explains,  the  mean- 
ing that  the  effect  "will  be,  whatever  supposition  we  may  make  in 
regard  to  all  other  things,"  or  that  the  sequence  will  "be  subject  to 
no  other  than  negative  conditions."  For  in  these  determinations  there 
does  not  lie  exclusively,  according  to  Mill,  a  probable  prediction  of 
the  future.  "It  is  necessary  to  our  using  the  word  cause,  that  we 
should  believe  not  only  that  the  antecedent  always  has  been  fol- 
lowed by  the  consequent,  but  that  as  long  as  the  present  constitution 
of  things  endures,  it  always  will  be  so."  Likewise,  Mill,  the  man  of 
research,  not  the  empiristic  logician,  asserts  that  there  belongs  to 
the  causal  law,  besides  this  generality  referring  to  all  possible  events 
of  uniform  sequence,  also  an  "undoubted  assurance;"  although  he 
could  have  here  referred  to  a  casual  remark  of  Hume.^  Such  an 
undoubted  assurance,  "that  for  every  event  .  .  .  there  is  a  law  to 
be  found,  if  we  only  know  where  to  find  it,"  evidently  does  not  know 
of  a  knowledge  referred  exclusively  to  experience. 

Hence,  if  the  causal  law  is,  as  empiricism  to  be  consistent  must 
maintain,  only  a  general  hypothesis  which  is  necessarily  subject  to 
verification  as  experience  progresses,  then  it  is  not  impossible  that  in 
the  course  of  experience  events  will  appear  that  are  not  preceded  or 
followed  uniformly  by  others,  and  that  accordingly  cannot  be  re- 
garded as  causes  or  effects.  According  to  this  interpretation  of  the 
causal  law,  such  exceptional  events,  whether  in  individual  or  in 
repeated  cases  of  perception,  must  be  just  as  possible  as  those  which 
in  the  course  of  preceding  experience  have  proved  themselves  to  be 
members  of  series  of  constant  sequence.  On  the  basis  of  previous 
experience,  we  should  only  have  the  right  to  say  that  such  exceptional 
cases  are  less  probable;  and  we  might  from  the  same  ground  expect 
that,  if  they  could  be  surely  determined,  they  would  only  have  to  be 
regarded  as  exceptions  to  the  rule  and  not,  possibly,  as  signs  of  a 
misunderstood  universal  non-uniformity  of  occurrence.  No  one 
wants  to  maintain  an  empirical  necessity,  that  is,  a  statement  that 
so  comprehends  a  present  experienoe  or  an  hypothesis  developed 

*  Logic,  hk.  ni,  ch.  v,  §  6,  and  end  of  §2.  Hume  says  in  a  note  to  section  vi  of  his 
Enquiry  concerning  Human  Understanding  :  "  We  ought  to  divide  arguments  into 
demonstrations,  proofs,  and  probabilities.  By  proofs  meaning  sucli  arguments  from 
experience  as  leave  no  room  for  doubt  or  opposition."  The  note  stands  in  evident 
contrast  to  the  well-known  remarks  at  the  beginning  of  section  iv,  pt.  i. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW    371 

on  the  basis  of  present  experience  that  its  contradictory  is  rationally- 
impossible.  An  event  preceded  by  no  other  immediately  and  uni- 
formly as  cause  would,  according  to  traditional  usage,  arise  out  of 
nothing.  An  event  that  was  followed  immediately  and  constantly 
by  no  other  would  accordingly  be  an  event  that  remained  without 
effect,  and,  did  it  pass  away,  it  must  disappear  into  nothing.  The 
old  thought,  well  known  in  its  scholastic  formulation,  ex  nihilo  nihil 
fit,  in  nihilum  nihil  potest  reverti,  is  only  another  expression  for  the 
causal  law  as  we  have  interpreted  it  above.  The  contradictories 
to  each  of  the  clauses  of  the  thought  just  formulated,  that  some- 
thing can  arise  out  of  nothing  and  pass  into  nothing,  remain  there- 
fore, as  a  consequence  of  empiricism,  an  improbable  thought,  to  be 
sure,  but  none  the  less  a  thought  to  which  a  real  possibility  must  be 
ascribed. 

It  was  in  all  probability  this  that  Stuart  Mill  wished  to  convey 
in  the  much-debated  passage:  "  I  am  convinced  that  any  one  accus- 
tomed to  abstraction  and  analysis,  who  will  fairly  exert  his  faculties 
for  the  purpose,  will,  when  his  imagination  has  once  learnt  to  enter- 
tain the  notion,  find  no  difficulty  in  conceiving  that  in  some  one,  for 
instance,  of  the  many  firmaments  into  which  sidereal  astronomy 
now  divides  the  universe,  events  may  succeed  one  another  at  random 
without  any  fixed  law;  nor  can  anything  in  our  experience,  or  in  our 
mental  nature,  constitute  a  sufficient,  or  indeed  any,  reason  for 
believing  that  this  is  nowhere  the  case."  For  Mill  immediately  calls 
our  attention  to  the  following:  "Were  we  to  suppose  (what  it  is 
perfectly  possible  to  imagine)  that  the  present  order  of  the  universe 
were  brought  to  an  end,  and  that  a  chaos  succeeded  in  which  there 
was  no  fixed  succession  of  events,  and  the  past  gave  no  assurance  of 
the  future;  if  a  human  being  were  miraculously  kept  alive  to  witness 
this  change,  he  surely  would  soon  cease  to  believe  in  any  uniformity, 
the  uniformity  itself  no  longer  existing."  ^ 

We  can  throw  light  from  another  side  upon  the  thought  that  lie? 
in  this  outcome  of  the  empiristic  interpretation  of  the  causal  law. 
If  we  still  desire  to  give  the  name  "effect"  to  an  event  that  is  pre- 
ceded uniformly  by  no  other,  and  that  we  therefore  have  to  regard 
as  arising  out  of  nothing,  then  we  must  say  that  it  is  the  effect  of 
itself,  that  is,  its  cause  lies  in  its  own  reality,  in  short,  that  it  is 
causa  sui.  Therefore  the  assumption  that  a  causa  sui  has  just  as 
much  real  possibility  as  have  the  causes  of  our  experience  which  are 
followed  uniformly  by  another  event,  is  a  necessary  consequence  of 
the  empiristic  view  of  causation.  This  much  only  remains  sure,  there 
is  nothing  contained  in  our  previous  experience  that  in  any  way 
assures  us  of  the  validity  of  this  possible  theory. 

The  empiristic  doctrine  of  causation  requires,  however,  still  fur- 
'  Logic,  bk.  iii,  ch.  xxi,  §  1. 


372  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

ther  conclusions.  Our  scientific,  no  less  than  our  practical  thought 
has  always  been  accustomed  to  regard  the  relation  between  cause 
and  effect  not  as  a  matter  of  mere  sequence,  not  therefore  as  a  mere 
formal  temporal  one.  Rather  it  has  always,  in  both  forms  of  our 
thought,  stood  for  a  real  relation,  that  is,  for  a  relation  of  dynamic 
dependence  of  effect  upon  cause.  Accordingly,  the  effect  arises  out 
of  the  cause,  is  engendered  through  it,  or  brought  forth  by  it. 

The  historical  development  of  this  dynamic  conception  of  cause 
is  well  known.  The  old  anthropopathic  interpretation,  which  inter- 
polates anthropomorphic  and  yet  superhuman  intervention  between 
the  events  that  follow  one  another  uniformly,  has  maintained  itself 
on  into  the  modern  metaphysical  hypotheses.  It  remains  standing 
wherever  God  is  assumed  as  the  first  cause  for  the  interaction  be- 
tween parts  of  reality.  It  is  made  obscure,  but  not  eliminated,  when, 
in  other  conceptions  of  the  world,  impersonal  nature,  fate,  neces- 
sity, the  absolute  identity,  or  an  abstraction  related  to  these,  ap- 
pears in  the  place  of  God.  On  the  other  hand,  it  comes  out  clearly 
wherever  these  two  tendencies  of  thought  unite  themselves  in  an 
anthropopathic  pantheism.  That  is,  it  rests  only  upon  a  differ- 
ence in  strength  between  the  governing  religious  and  scientific  in- 
terests, whether  or  not  the  All-One  which  unfolds  itself  in  the 
interconnection  and  content  of  reality  is  thought  of  more  as  the  im- 
manent God,  or  more  as  substance.  Finally,  we  do  not  change  our 
position,  if  the  absolute,  self-active  being  (in  all  these  theories  a  first 
cause  is  presupposed  as  causa  sui)  is  degraded  to  a  non-intellectual 
will. 

However,  the  dynamic  interpretation  of  cause  has  not  remained 
confined  to  the  field  of  these  general  speculations,  just  because  it 
commanded  that  field  so  early.  There  is  a  second  branch,  likewise 
early  evolved  from  the  stem  of  the  anthropopathic  interpretation, 
the  doctrine  that  the  causal  relations  of  dependence  are  effected 
through  "forces."  These  forces  adhere  to,  or  dwell  in,  the  ultimate 
physical  elements  which  are  thought  of  as  masses.  Again,  as  spiritual 
forces  they  belong  to  the  "soul,"  which  in  turn  is  thought  of  as  a 
substance.  In  the  modern  contrast  between  attractive  and  repulsive 
forces,  there  lies  a  remnant  of  the  Empedoklean  opposition  between 
Love  and  Hate.  In  the  various  old  and  new  hylozoistie  tendencies, 
the  concepts  of  force  and  its  correlate,  mass,  are  eclectically  united. 
In  consistent  materialism  as  well  as  spiritualism,  and  in  the  abstract 
dynamism  of  energetics,  the  one  member  is  robbed  of  its  independence 
or  even  rejected  in  favor  of  the  other.^ 

'  Alongside  of  these  d^mamic  theories,  there  are  to  be  found  mechanical  ones 
that  arose  just  as  early  and  from  the  same  source,  Aaz.,  the  practical  Weltan- 
schauung. It  is  not  part  of  our  purpose  to  discuss  them.  Their  first  scientific 
expression  is  to  be  found  in  the  doctrine  of  effluences  and  pores  in  Empedokles 
and  in  Atomism. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW    373 

It  is  evident  in  what  light  all  these  dynamic  conceptions  appear, 
when  looked  at  from  the  standpoint  of  consistent  extreme  empiricism. 
These  "forces,"  to  consider  here  only  this  one  of  the  dynamic  hypo- 
theses, help  to  explain  nothing.  The  physical  forces,  or  those  which 
give  rise  to  movement,  are  evidently  not  given  to  us  as  contents  of 
sense  perception,  and  at  the  most  they  can  be  deduced  as  non-sen- 
suous foundations,  not  as  contents  of  possible  sense  perception.  The 
often  and  variously  expressed  belief  that  self  perception  reveals  to 
us  here  what  our  senses  leave  hidden  has  proved  itself  to  be  in  all  its 
forms  a  delusion.  The  forces  whose  existence  we  assume  have  then 
an  intuitable  content  only  in  so  far  as  they  get  it  through  the  uniform- 
ities present  in  repeated  perceptions,  which  uniformities  are  to  be 
"explained"  through  them.  But  right  here  their  assumption  proves 
itself  to  be  not  only  superfluous  but  even  misleading;  for  it  makes  us 
believe  that  we  have  offered  an  explanation,  whereas  in  reality  we 
have  simply  duplicated  the  given  by  means  of  a  fiction,  quite  after  the 
fashion  of  the  Platonic  doctrine  of  ideas.  This  endeavor  to  give  the 
formal  temporal  relations  between  events,  which  we  interpret  as 
causes  and  effects,  a  dynamic  real  substructure,  shows  itself  thus  to 
be  worthless  in  its  contributions  to  our  thought.  The  same  holds 
true  of  every  other  dynamic  hypothesis.  The  critique  called  forth 
by  these  contributions  establishes  therefore  only  the  validity  of  the 
empiristic  interpretation. 

If,  however,  we  have  once  come  so  far,  we  may  not  hold  ourselves 
back  from  the  final  step.  Empiricism  has  long  ago  taken  this  step, 
and  the  most  consistent  among  its  modern  German  representatives 
has  aroused  anew  the  impulses  that  make  it  necessary.  Indeed,  if 
we  start  from  the  empiristic  presuppositions,  we  must  recognize  that 
there  lies  not  only  in  the  assumption  of  forces,  but  even  in  the  habit 
of  speaking  of  causes  and  effects,  "a  clear  trace  of  fetishism."  We 
are  not  then  surprised  when  the  statement  is  made:  The  natural 
science  of  the  future,  and  accordingly  science  in  general,  will,  it  is 
to  be  hoped,  set  aside  these  concepts  also  on  account  of  their  formal 
obscurity.  For,  so  it  is  explained,  repetitions  of  like  cases  in  which 
a  is  always  connected  mth  h,  namely,  in  which  like  results  are  found 
under  like  circumstances,  in  short,  the  essence  of  the  connection  of 
cause  and  effect,  exists  only  in  the  abstraction  that  is  necessary  to 
enable  us  to  repicture  the  facts.  In  nature  itself  there  are  no  causes 
and  effects.   Die  Natur  ist  nur  einmal  da. 

It  is,  again,  Stuart  Mill,  the  man  of  research,  not  the  empiricist,  that 
opposes  this  conclusion,  and  indeed  opposes  it  in  the  form  that 
Auguste  Comte  had  given  it  in  connection  with  thoughts  that  can 
be  read  into  Hume's  doctrine.  Comte's  "objection  to  the  word 
cause  is  a  mere  matter  of  nomenclature,  in  which,  as  a  matter  of 
nomenclature,  I  consider  him  to  be  entirely  wrong.  .  .  .  By  reject- 


374  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

ing  this  form  of  expression,  M.  Comte  leaves  himself  without  any 
term  for  marking  a  distinction  which,  however  incorrectly  expressed, 
is  not  only  real,  but  is  one  of  the  fundamental  distinctions  in  science."  ^ 
For  my  own  part,  the  right  seems  to  be  on  the  side  of  Comte 
and  his  recent  followers  in  showing  the  old  nomenclature  to  be  worn 
out,  if  viewed  from  the  standpoint  of  empiricism.  If  the  relation 
between  cause  and  effect  consists  alone  in  the  uniformity  of  sequence 
which  is  hypothetically  warranted  by  experience,  then  it  can  be 
only  misleading  to  employ  words  for  the  members  of  this  purely 
formal  relation  that  necessarily  have  a  strong  tang  of  real  dynamic 
dependence.  In  fact,  they  give  the  connection  in  question  a  peculiarity 
that,  according  to  consistent  empiricism,  it  does  not  possess.  The 
question  at  issue  in  the  empiristically  interpreted  causal  relation  is 
a  formal  functional  one,  which  is  not  essentially  different,  as  Ernst 
Mach  incidentally  acknowledges,  from  the  interdependence  of  the 
sides  and  angles  of  a  triangle. 

Here  two  extremes  meet.  Spinoza,  the  most  consistent  of  the  dog- 
matic rationalists,  finds  himself  compelled  in  his  formulation  of  the 
analytic  interpretation  of  the  causal  relation  handed  down  to  him 
to  transform  it  into  a  mathematical  one.  Mach,  the  most  consistent 
of  recent  German  empiricists,  finds  himself  compelled  to  recognize 
that  the  empirically  synthetic  relation  between  cause  and  effect 
includes  no  other  form  of  dependence  than  that  which  is  present 
in  the  functional  mathematical  relations.  (In  Germany  empiricism 
steeped  in  natural  science  has  supplanted  the  naive  materialism 
saturated  with  natural  science.)  That  the  mathematical  relations 
must  likewise  be  subjected  to  a  purely  empirical  interpretation, 
which  even  Hume  denied  them,  is  a  matter  of  course. 

However,  this  agreement  of  two  opposing  views  is  no  proof  that 
empiricism  is  on  the  right  road.  The  empiristic  conclusions  to  which 
we  have  given  our  attention  do  not  succeed  in  defining  adequately 
the  specific  nature  of  the  causal  relation;  on  the  contrary,  they 
compel  us  to  deny  such  a  relation.  Thus  they  cast  aside  the  concept 
that  we  have  endeavored  to  define,  that  is,  the  judgment  in  which 
we  have  to  comprehend  whatever  is  peculiar  to  the  causal  connection. 
But  one  does  not  untie  a  knot  by  denying  that  it  exists. 

It  follows  from  this  self-destruction  of  the  empiristic  causal  hypo- 
thesis that  an  additional  element  of  thought  must  be  contained  in  the 
relation  of  cause  and  effect  besides  the  elements  of  reproductive 
recognition  and  those  of  identification  and  discrimination,  all  of 
which  are  involved  in  the  abstract  comprehension  of  uniform  se- 
quence. The  characteristics  of  the  causal  connection  revealed  by  our 
previous  analysis  constitute  the  necessary  and  perhaps  adequate 
conditions  for  combining  the  several  factual  perceptions  into  the 
*  Logic,  bk.  iii,  ch.  v,  §  6. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL   LAW    875 

abstract  registering  idea  of  uniform  sequence.  We  may,  therefore, 
expect  to  find  that  the  element  sought  for  lies  in  the  tendency  to 
extend  the  demand  for  causal  connections  over  the  entire  field  of 
possible  experience;  and  perhaps  we  may  at  the  same  time  arrive 
at  the  condition  which  led  Hume  and  Mill  to  recognize  the  complete 
universality  of  the  causal  law  in  spite  of  the  exclusively  empirical 
content  that  they  had  ascribed  to  it.  In  this  further  analysis  also 
we  have  to  draw  from  the  nature  of  our  thought  itself  the  means  of 
guiding  our  investigation. 

In  the  first  place,  all  thought  has  a  formal  necessity  which  reveals 
itself  in  the  general  causal  law  no  less  than  in  every  individual 
thought  process,  that  is,  in  every  valid  judgment.  The  meaning  of 
this  formal  necessity  of  thought  is  easily  determined.  If  we  presup- 
pose, for  example,  that  I  recognize  a  surface  which  lies  before  me 
as  green,  then  the  perception  judgment,  "This  surface  is  green," 
that  is,  the  apprehension  of  the  present  perceptive  content  in  the 
fundamental  form  of  discursive  thought,  repeats  with  predicative 
necessity  that  which  is  presented  to  me  in  the  content  of  perception. 
The  necessity  of  thought  contained  in  this  perception  judgment,  as 
mutatis  mutandis  in  every  affirmative  judgment  meeting  the  logical 
conditions,  is  recognizable  through  the  fact  that  the  contradictory 
judgment,  "This  surface  is  not  green,"  is  impossible  for  our  thought 
under  the  presupposition  of  the  given  content  of  perception  and  of 
our  nomenclature.  It  contradicts  itself.  I  can  express  the  contradict- 
ory proposition,  for  instance,  in  order  to  deceive;  but  I  cannot  really 
pass  the  judgment  that  is  contained  in  it.  It  lies  in  the  very  nature 
of  our  thought  that  the  predicate  of  an  assertive  judgment  can  con- 
tain only  whatever  belongs  as  an  element  of  some  sort  (characteristic, 
attribute,  state,  relation)  to  the  subject  content  in  the  wider  sense. 
The  same  formal  necessity  of  thought,  to  give  a  further  instance,  is 
present  in  the  thought  process  of  mediate  syllogistic  predication. 
The  conclusion  follows  necessarily  from  the  premises,  for  example, 
the  judgment,  "All  bodies  are  divisible,"  from  the  propositions, 
"  All  bodies  are  extended,"  and,  "  Whatever  is  extended  is  divisible." 

These  elementary  remarks  are  not  superfluous;  for  they  make 
clear  that  the  casually  expressed  assertion  of  modern  natural  scien- 
tific empiricism,  declaring  in  effect  that  there  is  no  such  thing  as 
necessity  of  thought,  goes  altogether  too  far.  Such  necessity  can 
have  an  admissible  meaning  only  in  so  far  as  it  denotes  that  in 
predicting  or  recounting  the  content  of  possible  experience  every  hypo- 
thesis is  possible  for  thought.  Of  course  it  is,  but  that  is  not 
the  subject  under  discussion. 

The  recognition  of  the  formal  necessity  of  thought  that  must  be 
presupposed  helps  us  to  define  our  present  question;  for  it  needs  no 
proof  that  this  formal  necessity  of  thought,  being  valid  for  every 


376  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

affirmative  judgment,  is  valid  also  for  each  particular  induction, 
and  again  for  the  general  causal  law.  If  in  the  course  of  our  per- 
ceptions we  meet  uniform  sequences,  then  the  judgment,  "These 
sequences  are  uniform,"  comprehends  the  common  content  of  many 
judgments  with  formal  necessity  of  thought.  Empiricism,  too,  does 
not  seriously  doubt  that  the  hypothesis  of  a  general  functional,  even 
though  only  temporal,  relation  between  cause  and  effect  is  deduced 
as  an  expectation  of  possible  experience  Tvith  necessity  from  our  real 
experience.  It  questions  only  the  doctrine  that  the  relation  between 
the  events  regarded  as  cause  and  effect  has  an}-  other  than  a  purely 
empirical  import.  The  reahty  of  an  event  that  is  preceded  and  fol- 
lowed uniformly  by  no  other  remains  for  this  view,  as  we  have  seen, 
a  possibiht}'  of  thought. 

In  opposition  to  empiricism,  we  now  formulate  the  thesis  to  be 
estabhshed:  Wherever  two  events  a  and  h  are  known  to  foUow  one 
another  uniformly  and  immediately,  there  we  must  require  ^ith 
formal  necessity  that  some  element  in  the  preceding  a  be  thought  of 
as  fundamental,  which  will  determine  sufficiently  6's  appearance  or 
make  that  appearance  necessary.  The  necessity  of  the  relation 
between  the  events  regarded  as  cause  and  effect  is,  therefore,  the 
question  at  issue. 

We  must  keep  in  mind  from  the  very  start  that  less  is  asserted  in 
this  formulation  than  we  are  apt  to  read  into  it.  It  states  merely 
that  something  in  a  must  be  thought  of  as  fundamental,  which  makes 
h  necessary.  On  the  other  hand,  it  saj's  nothing  as  to  what  this 
fundamental  something  is,  or  how  it  is  constituted.  It  leaves  entirely 
undecided  whether  or  not  this  something  that  our  thought  must 
necessarily  postulate  is  a  possible  content  of  perception  or  can  be- 
come such,  accordingly  whether  or  not  it  can  become  an  object  of 
our  knowledge,  or  whether  or  not  it  lies  beyond  the  bounds  of  all 
our  possible  experience  and  hence  all  our  possible  knowledge.  It 
contains  nothing  whatsoever  that  teUs  us  how  the  determination 
of  h  takes  place  through  a.  The  word  "fundamental"  is  intended 
to  express  all  this  absence  of  determination. 

Thus  we  hope  to  show  a  necessity  of  thought  pecuhar  to  the  rela- 
tion between  cause  and  effect.  This  is  the  same  as  saying  that  our 
proof  wiU  estabhsh  the  logical  impossibility  of  the  contradictory 
assertion;  for  the  logical  impossibility  of  the  contradictory  assertion 
is  the  only  criterion  of  logical  necessit}'.  Thus  the  proof  that  we  seek 
can  be  given  only  indirectly.  In  the  course  of  this  proof,  we  can 
disregard  the  immediacy  of  the  constant  sequence  and  confine  our 
attention  to  the  uniformit}'  of  the  sequence,  not  only  for  the  sake  of 
brcAity,  but  also  because,  as  we  have  seen,  we  have  the  right  to 
speak  of  near  and  remote  causes.    We  may  then  proceed  as  follows. 

If  there  is  not  something  fundamental  in  a  constant  antecedent 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW    377 

event  a,  which  determines  necessarily  the  constant  subsequent 
appearance  of  one  and  the  same  h,  —  that  is,  if  there  is  nothing 
fundamental  which  makes  this  appearance  necessary,  —  then  we 
must  assume  that  also  c  or  d  .  .  .  ,  in  short,  any  event  you  will, 
we  dare  not  say  "foUows  upon,"  but  appears  after  a  in  irregular 
alternation  with  h.  This  assumption,  however,  is  impossible  for  our 
thought,  because  it  is  in  contradiction  with  our  experience,  on  the 
basis  of  which  our  causal  thought  has  been  developed.  Therefore 
the  assumption  of  a  something  that  is  fundamental  in  a,  and  that 
determines  sufficiently  and  necessarilj"  the  appearance  of  b,  is  a 
necessity  for  our  thought. 

The  assertion  of  this  logical  impossibihty  (Denkunnidglichkeit) 
will  at  once  appear  thoroughly  paradoxical.  The  reader,  merely 
recaUing  the  results  of  the  empiristic  interpretation  given  above, 
will  immediately  say:  "The  assumption  that  a  h  does  not  follow 
constantly  upon  an  a,  but  that  sometimes  b,  sometimes  c,  some- 
times d  .  .  .  irregularly  appears,  is  in  contradiction  only  with  aU 
our  previous  experience,  but  it  is  not  on  this  account  a  logical  im- 
possibiht3\  It  is  merely  improbable."  The  reader  -otU  appeal  espe- 
cially to  the  discussion  of  Stuart  ]\IiU,  already  quoted,  in  which  ]\Iill 
pictures  in  concreto  such  an  improbable  logical  impossibiht}^,  and 
therefore  at  the  same  time  establishes  it  in  fact.  Again,  the  reader 
may  bring  forward  the  words  in  which  Helmholtz  introduces  intel- 
lectual beings  of  only  two  dimensions.  "  By  the  much  misused 
expression,  'to  be  able  to  imagine  to  one's  self,'  or,  'to  think  how 
something  happens,'  I  understand  (and  I  do  not  see  how  anybody 
can  understand  anything  else  thereb}^  without  robbing  the  expression 
of  aU  meaning)  that  one  can  picture  to  one's  self  the  series  of  sense 
impressions  which  one  would  have  if  such  a  thing  actuall}'  took 
place  in  an  indi\ddual  case."^ 

Nevertheless,  pertinent  as  are  these  and  similar  objections,  they 
are  not  able  to  stand  the  test.  We  ask:  "Is  in  fact  a  world,  or  even 
a  portion  of  our  world,  possible  for  thought  that  display's  through  an 
absolutely  irregular  alternation  of  events  a  chaos  in  the  full  sense; 
or  is  the  attempt  to  picture  such  a  chaos  only  a  mere  play  of  words 
to  which  not  even  our  imagination,  not  to  mention  our  thought,  can 
give  a  possible  meaning?  " 

Perhaps  we  shall  reach  a  conclusion  by  the  easiest  way,  if  we 
subject  ]\IiU's  description  to  a  test.  If  we  reduce  it  to  the  several 
propositions  it  contains,  we  get  the  following:  (1)  Every  one  is  able 
to  picture  to  himself  in  hi's  imagination  a  reahty  in  which  events 
follow  one  another  without  rule,  that  is,  so  that  after  an  event  a 
now  b  appears,  now  c,  etc.,  in  complete  irregularity.    (2)  The  idea  of 

*  Vortrcge  und  Reden,  bd.  ii,  "Uber  den  Ursprung  und  die  Bedeutung  der 
geometrischen  Axiome." 


378  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

such  a  chaos  accordingly  contradicts  neither  the  nature  of  our  mind 
nor  our  experience.  (3)  Neither  the  former  nor  the  latter  gives  us 
sufficient  reason  to  believe  that  such  an  irregular  alternation  does 
not  actually  exist  somewhere  in  the  observable  world.  (4)  If  such 
a  chaos  should  be  presented  to  us  as  fact,  that  is,  if  we  were  in  a 
position  to  outlive  such  an  alternation,  then  the  belief  in  the  uniform- 
ity of  time  relations  would  soon  cease. 

Every  one  would  subscribe  to  the  last  of  these  four  theses,  im- 
mediately upon  such  a  chaos  being  admitted  to  be  a  possibility  of 
thought;  that  is,  he  would  unless  he  shared  the  rationalistic  con- 
viction that  our  thought  constitutes  an  activity  absolutely  inde- 
pendent of  all  experience.  We  must  simply  accept  this  conclusion 
on  the  ground  of  the  previous  discussion  and  of  a  point  still  to  be 
brought  forward. 

If  we  grant  this  conclusion,  however,  then  it  follows,  on  the 
ground  of  our  previous  demonstration  of  the  reproductive  and 
recognitive,  as  well  as  thought  elements  involved  in  the  uniform 
sequence,  that  the  irregularity  in  the  appearance  of  the  events, 
assumed  in  such  a  chaos,  can  bring  about  an  absolutely  relationless 
alternation  of  impressions  for  the  subject  that  we  should  presuppose 
to  be  doing  the  perceiving.  If  we  still  wish  to  call  it  perception,  it 
would  remain  only  a  perception  in  which  no  component  of  its  con- 
tent could  be  related  to  the  others,  a  perception,  therefore,  in  which 
not  even  the  synthesis  of  the  several  perception  contents  could  be 
apprehended  as  such.  That  is,  every  combination  of  the  different 
perception  contents,  by  which  they  become  components  of  one  and 
the  same  perception,  presupposes,  as  we  have  seen,  those  repro- 
ductive and  recognitive  acts  in  revival  which  are  possible  only  where 
uniformities  of  succession  (and  of  coexistence)  exist.  Again,  every 
act  of  attention  involved  in  identifying  and  discriminating,  which 
likewise  we  have  seen  to  be  possible  only  if  we  presuppose  uniform- 
ities in  the  given  contents  of  perception,  must  necessarily  disappear 
when  we  presuppose  the  chaotic  content;  and  yet  they  remain 
essential  to  the  very  idea  of  such  a  chaos.  A  relationless  chaos  is 
after  all  nothing  else  than  a  system  of  relations  thought  of  without 
relations!  That  the  same  contradiction  obtains  also  in  the  mere 
mental  picturing  of  a  manifold  of  chaotic  impressions  needs  no 
discussion;  for  the  productive  imagination  as  well  as  the  reproduct- 
ive is  no  less  dependent  than  is  our  perceptive  knowledge  upon  the 
reproductive  recognition  and  upon  the  processes  of  identifying  and 
discriminating. 

Thus  the  mental  image  of  a  chaos  could  be  formed  only  through 
an  extended  process  of  ideation,  which  itself  presupposes  as  active 
in  it  all  that  must  be  denied  through  the  very  nature  of  the  image. 
A  relationless  knowledge,  a  relationless  abstraction,  a  relationless 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW      379 

reproduction  or  recognition,  a  relationless  identification  or  discrim- 
ination, in  short,  a  relationless  thought,  are,  as  phrases,  one  and 
all  mere  contradictions.  We  cannot  picture  "through  our  relating 
thought,"  to  use  Helmholtz's  expression,  nor  even  in  our  imagination, 
the  sense  impressions  that  we  should  have  if  our  thought  were  re- 
lationless, that  is,  were  nullified  in  its  very  components  and  presup- 
positions. In  the  case  of  Helmholtz's  two  dimensional  beings,  the 
question  at  issue  was  not  regarding  the  setting  aside  of  the  conditions 
of  our  thought  and  the  substituting  conditions  contradictory  to 
them,  but  regarding  the  setting  aside  of  a  part  of  the  content  of  our 
sense  intuition,  meanwhile  retaining  the  conditions  and  forms 
peculiar  to  our  thought.  In  this  case,  therefore,  we  have  a  permissible 
fiction,  whereas  in  Mill's  chaos  we  have  an  unthinkable  thought. 

Again,  the  sense  impressions  that  must  be  presupposed  in  an 
inherently  relationless  chaos  have  no  possible  relation  to  the  world 
of  our  perception,  whose  components  are  universally  related  to 
each  other  through  the  uniformities  of  their  coexistences  and  se- 
quences. Accordingly,  the  remark  with  which  Helmholtz  concludes 
the  passage  above  quoted  holds,  mutatis  mutandis,  here  also.  "  If  there 
is  no  sense  impression  known  that  stands  in  relation  to  an  event 
which  has  never  been  observed  (by  us),  as  would  be  the  case  for  us 
were  there  a  motion  toward  a  fourth  dimension,  and  for  those  two 
dimensional  beings  were  there  a  motion  toward  our  third  dimension; 
then  it  foUows  that  such  an  '  idea '  is  impossible,  as  much  so  as  that 
a  man  completely  blind  from  childhood  should  be  able  to  '  imagine ' 
the  colors,  if  we  could  give  him  too  a  conceptual  description  of  them." 

Hence  the  first  of  the  theses  in  which  we  summed  up  Stuart 
Mill's  assumptions  must  be  rejected.  With  it  go  also  the  second  and 
third.  In  this  case  we  need  not  answer  the  question:  In  how  far 
do  these  theses  correspond  to  Mill's  own  statements  regarding  the 
absolute  surety  and  universality  of  the  causal  law? 

We  have  now  found  what  we  sought,  in  order  to  establish  as  a 
valid  assertion  the  seeming  paradox  in  the  proof  of  the  necessity 
that  we  ascribe  to  the  relation  between  cause  and  effect.  We  have 
proved  that  the  assumption  of  a  completely  irregular  and  therefore 
relationless  alternation  of  impressions  contradicts  not  only  our 
experience,  but  even  the  conditions  of  our  thought;  for  these  pre- 
suppose the  uniformities  of  the  impressions,  and  consequently  our 
ability  to  relate  them,  all  which  was  eliminated  from  our  hypothetical 
chaos.  Hence  we  have  also  established  that  a  necessary  relation  is 
implied  in  the  thought  of  a  constant  sequence  of  events,  which 
makes  the  uniformly  following  b  really  dependent  upon  the  uniformly 
preceding  a. 

From  still  another  side,  we  can  make  clear  the  necessity  asserted 


380  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

in  the  relation  of  cause  and  effect.  We  found  that  the  connection 
between  each  dej&nite  cause  and  its  effect  is  an  empirically  synthetic 
one  and  has  as  its  warrant  merely  experience.  We  saw  further  that 
the  necessity  inherent  in  the  causal  connection  contains  merely  the 
demand  that  there  shall  be  something  fundamental  in  the  constantly 
preceding  a  which  makes  the  appearance  of  b  necessary;  not,  however, 
that  it  informs  us  what  this  efficacy  really  is,  and  hence  also  not  that 
it  informs  us  how  this  efficacy  brings  about  its  effect.  Finally,  we 
had  to  urge  that  every  induction,  the  most  general  no  less  than  the 
most  particular,  depends  upon  the  presupposition  that  the  same 
causes  will  be  given  in  the  reality  not  yet  observed  as  in  that  already 
observed.  This  expectation  is  warranted  by  no  necessity  of  thought, 
not  even  by  that  involved  in  the  relation  of  cause  and  effect;  for 
this  relation  begins  for  future  experience  only  when  the  presup- 
position that  the  same  causes  will  be  found  in  it  is  assumed  as  ful- 
filled.^ This  expectation  is  then  dependent  solely  upon  previous 
experience,  whose  servants  we  are,  whose  lords  we  can  never  be. 
Therefore,  every  induction  is  an  hypothesis  requiring  the  verification 
of  a  broader  experience,  since,  in  its  work  of  widening  and  completing 
our  knowledge,  it  leads  us  beyond  the  given  experience  to  a  possible 
one.  In  this  respect  we  can  call  all  inductive  thought  empirical, 
that  is,  thought  that  begins  with  experience,  is  directed  to  experience, 
and  in  its  results  is  referred  to  experience.  The  office  of  this  progress- 
ing empirical  thought  is  accordingly  to  form  hypotheses  from  which 
the  data  of  perception  can  be  regressively  deduced,  and  by  means  of 
which  they  can  be  exhibited  as  cases  of  known  relations  of  our  well- 
ordered  experience,  and  thus  can  be  explained. 

The  way  of  forming  hypotheses  can  be  divided  logically  into 
different  sections  which  can  readily  be  made  clear  by  an  example. 
The  police  magistrate  finds  a  human  corpse  under  circumstances 
that  eliminate  the  possibihty  of  accident,  natural  death,  or  suicide; 
in  short,  that  indicate  an  act  of  violence  on  the  part  of  another  man. 
The  general  hypothesis  that  he  has  here  to  do  with  a  crime  against 
life  forms  the  guide  of  his  investigation.  The  result  of  the  circum- 
stantial evidence,  which  we  presuppose  as  necessary,  furnishes  then 
a  special  hypothesis  as  following  from  the  general  hypothesis. 

It  is  clear  that  this  division  holds  for  all  cases  of  forming  hypo- 
theses. A  general  hypothesis  serves  every  special  hypothesis  as  a 
heuristic  principle.  In  the  former  we  comprehend  the  causal  explan- 
ation indicated  immediately  by  the  facts  revealed  to  our  perception 

^  The  only  empiricism  which  can  maintain  that  the  same  causes  would,  in  con- 
formity with  the  causal  law,  be  given  in  the  unobserved  reality,  is  one  which  puts 
all  events  that  can  be  regarded  as  causes  in  the  immediately  given  content  of 
perception  as  its  members.  Such  a  view  is  not  to  be  fovmd  in  Mill;  and  it  stands 
so  completely  in  the  way  of  all  further  analysis  required  of  us  by  every  perception 
of  events  that  no  attention  has  been  paid  in  the  text  to  this  extreme  of  extremes. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE  CAUSAL  LAW    381 

in  the  special  case.  It  contains,  as  we  might  also  express  it,  the 
genus  to  the  specific  limitations  of  the  more  exact  investigation. 
But  each  of  these  general  hypotheses  is  a  modification  of  the  most 
general  form  of  building  hypotheses,  which  we  have  already  come 
to  know  as  the  condition  of  the  validity  of  all  inductive  inferences, 
that  is,  as  the  condition  for  the  necessity  of  their  deduction,  and, 
consequently,  as  the  condition  for  the  thought  that  like  causes  will 
be  given  in  the  reality  not  yet  observed  as  in  that  already  observed. 
We  have  further  noticed  that  in  this  most  general  form  of  building 
hypotheses  there  lie  two  distinct  and  different  valid  assumptions: 
beside  the  empirical  statement  that  like  causes  will  be  given,  which 
gives  the  inductive  conclusion  the  hypothetical  form,  there  stands 
the  judgment  that  like  causes  bring  forth  like  effects,  a  corollary  of 
the  causal  law.  The  real  dependence  of  the  effect  upon  the  cause, 
presupposed  by  this  second  proposition  and  the  underlying  causal 
law,  is  not,  as  was  the  other  assumption,  an  hypothesis,  but  a  neces- 
sary requirement  or  postulate  of  our  thought.  Its  necessity  arises  out 
of  our  thought,  because  our  experience  reveals  uniformity  in  the 
sequence  of  events.  From  this  point  of  view,  therefore,  the  causal 
law  appears  as  a  postulate  of  our  thought,  grounded  upon  the  uni- 
formity in  the  sequence  of  events.  It  underlies  every  special  case  of 
constructing  hypotheses  as  well  as  the  expectation  that  like  causes 
will  be  given  in  the  reality  not  yet  observed. 

Mill's  logic  of  induction  contains  the  same  fault  as  that  already 
present  in  Hume's  psychological  theory  of  cause.  Hume  makes 
merely  the  causal  law  itself  responsible  for  our  inductive  inferences, 
and  accordingly  (as  Mill  likewise  wrongly  assumes)  for  our  inferences 
in  general.  But  we  recognize  how  rightly  Mill  came  to  assert,  in 
contradiction  to  his  empiristic  presuppositions,  that  the  causal  law 
offers  "an  undoubted  assurance  of  an  invariable,  universal,  and 
unconditional,"  that  is,  necessary,  sequence  of  events,  from  which 
no  seeming  irregularity  of  occurrence  and  no  gap  in  our  experience 
can  lead  us  astray,  as  long  as  experience  offers  uniformities  of  se- 
quence. 

Rationalism  is  thus  in  the  right,  when  it  regards  the  necessary 
connection  as  an  essential  characteristic  of  the  relation  between 
cause  and  effect,  that  is,  recognizes  in  it  a  relation  of  real  dependence. 
At  this  point  Kant  and  Schopenhauer  have  had  a  profounder  insight 
than  Hume  and  Stuart  Mill.  Especially  am  I  glad  to  be  in  agreement 
with  Lotze  on  a  point  which  he  reached  by  a  different  route  and 
from  essentially  different  presuppositions.  Lotze  distinguishes  in 
pure  logic  between  postulates,  hypotheses,  and  fictions.  He  does 
not  refer  the  term  "postulate"  exclusively  to  the  causal  law  which 
governs  our  entire  empirical  thought  in  its  formation  of  hypotheses, 
but  gives  the  term  a  wider  meaning.  "  Postulates  "  are  only  corollaries 


382  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

from  the  inductive  fundamental  form  of  all  hypothesis  construction, 
and  correspond  essentially  to  what  we  have  called  general  or  heuristic 
hypotheses.  His  determination  of  the  validity  of  these  postulates, 
however,  implies  the  position  to  be  assigned  to  the  causal  law  and 
therefore  not  to  those  heuristic  hypotheses.  "  The  postulate  is  not  an 
assumption  that  we  can  make  or  refrain  from  making,  or,  again,  in 
whose  place  we  can  substitute  another.  It  is  rather  an  (absolutely) 
necessary  assumption  without  which  the  content  of  the  view  at 
issue  would  contradict  the  laws  of  our  thought."  ^ 

Still  the  decision  that  we  have  reached  is  not  on  this  account  in 
favor  of  rationalism,  as  this  is  represented  for  instance  by  Kant  and 
his  successors  down  to  our  own  time,  and  professed  by  Lotze  in  the 
passage  quoted,  when  he  speaks  of  an  absolute  necessity  for  thought. 
We  found  that  the  causal  law  requires  a  necessary  connection  be- 
tween events  given  us  in  constant  sequence.  It  is  not,  however, 
on  that  account  a  law  of  our  thought  or  of  a  "pure  understanding" 
which  would  be  absolutely  independent  of  all  experience.  When  we 
take  into  consideration  the  evolution  of  the  organic  world  of  which 
we  are  members,  then  we  must  say  that  our  intellect,  that  is,  our 
ideation  and  with  it  our  sense  perception,  has  evolved  in  us  in  ac- 
cordance with  the  influences  to  which  we  have  been  subjected.  The 
common  elements  in  the  different  contents  of  perception  which  have 
arisen  out  of  other  psychical  elements,  seemingly  first  in  the  brute 
world,  are  not  only  an  occasion,  but  also  an  efficient  cause,  for  the 
evolution  of  our  processes  of  reproduction,  in  which  our  memory 
and  imagination  as  well  as  our  knowledge  and  thought,  psycholog- 
ically considered,  come  to  pass.  The  causal  law,  which  the  critical 
analysis  of  the  material-scientific  methods  shows  to  be  a  funda- 
mental condition  of  empirical  thought,  in  its  requirement  that  the 
events  stand  as  causes  and  effects  in  necessary  connection,  or  real 
dependence,  comprehends  these  uniform  contents  of  perception 
only  in  the  way  peculiar  to  our  thought. 

Doubtless  our  thought  gives  a  connection  to  experience  through 
this  its  requirement  which  experience  of  itself  could  not  offer.  The 
necessary  connection  of  effect  with  cause,  or  the  real  dependence  of 
the  former  upon  the  latter,  is  not  a  component  of  possible  percep- 
tion. This  requirement  of  our  thought  does  not,  however,  become 
thereby  independent  of  the  perceptive  elements  in  the  presupposi- 
tions involved  in  the  uniformity  of  sequence.  The  a  priori  in  the 
sense  of  "innate  ideas,"  denoting  either  these  themselves  or  an  ab- 
solutely a  priori  conformity  to  law  that  underlies  them,  for  instance, 
our  "spontaneity,"  presupposes  in  principle  that  our  "soul"  is  an 
independently  existing  substance  in  the  traditional  metaphysical 
sense  down  to  the  time  of  Locke.  Kant's  rationalistic  successors, 
^Logic,  1874,  buch  ii,  kap.  viii. 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE   CAUSAL   LAW    383 

for  the  most  part,  lost  sight  of  the  fact  that  Kant  had  retained  these 
old  metaphysical  assumptions  in  his  interpretation  of  the  tran- 
scendental conditions  of  empirical  interaction  and  in  his  cosmo- 
logical  doctrine  of  freedom.  The  common  root  of  the  sensibility  and 
of  the  understanding  as  the  higher  faculty  of  knowledge  remains  for 
Kant  the  substantial  force  of  the  soul,  which  expresses  itself  (just  as 
in  Leibnitz)  as  vis  passiva  and  vis  activa.  The  modern  doctrine  of 
evolution  has  entirely  removed  the  foundation  from  this  rationalism 
which  had  been  undermined  ever  since  Locke's  criticism  of  the  tra- 
ditional concept  of  substance. 

To  refer  again  briefly  to  a  second  point  in  which  the  foregoing 
results  differ  from  the  Kantian  rationalism  as  well  as  from  empiricism 
since  Hume:  The  postulate  of  a  necessary  connection  between 
cause  and  effect,  as  we  have  seen,  in  no  way  implies  the  consequence 
that  the  several  inductions  lose  the  character  of  hypotheses.  This 
does  not  follow  merely  from  the  fact  that  all  inductions  besides  the 
causal  law  include  the  hypothetical  thought  that  the  same  causes 
will  be  given  in  the  reality  not  yet  observed  as  appear  in  that  already 
observed.  The  hypothetical  character  of  all  inductive  inferences  is 
rather  revealed  through  the  circumstance  that  in  the  causal  postulate 
absolutely  nothing  is  contained  regarding  what  the  efficacy  in  the 
causes  is,  and  how  this  efficacy  arises. 

Only  such  consequences  of  the  foregoing  interpretation  of  the 
causal  law  and  of  its  position  as  one  of  the  bases  of  all  scientific  con- 
struction of  hypotheses  may  be  pointed  out,  in  conclusion,  as  will 
help  to  make  easier  the  understanding  of  the  interpretation  itself. 

The  requirement  of  a  necessary  connection,  or  dependence,  is 
added  by  our  thought  to  the  reproductive  and  recognitive  presup- 
positions that  are  contained  in  the  uniformity  of  the  sequence  of 
events.  If  this  necessary  connection  be  taken  objectively,  then 
it  reveals  as  its  correlate  the  requirement  of  a  real  dependence  of 
effect  upon  cause.  We  come  not  only  upon  often  and  variously 
used  rationalistic  thoughts,  but  also  upon  old  and  unchangeable 
components  of  all  empirical  scientific  thought,  when  we  give  the 
name  "force  "  to  the  efficacy  that  underlies  causes.  The  old  postu- 
late of  a  dynamic  intermediary  between  the  events  that  follow  one 
another  constantly  retains  for  us,  therefore,  its  proper  meaning. 
We  admit  without  hesitation  that  the  word  "force"  suggests  fetish- 
ism more  than  do  the  words  "cause"  and  "effect;"  but  we  do  not 
see  how  this  can  to  any  degree  be  used  as  a  counter-argument.  All 
words  that  were  coined  in  the  olden  time  to  express  thoughts  of  the 
practical  Weltanschauung  have  an  archaic  tang.  Likewise  all  of  our 
science  and  the  greater  part  of  our  nomenclature  have  arisen  out  of 
the  sphere  of  thought  contained  in  the  practical  Weltanschauung, 


384  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

which  centred  early  in  fetishism  and  related  thoughts.  If,  then,  we 
try  to  free  our  scientific  terminology  from  such  words,  we  must 
seek  refuge  in  the  Utopia  of  a  lingua  universalis,  in  short,  we  must 
endeavor  to  speak  a  language  which  would  make  science  a  secret 
of  the  few.  Or  will  any  one  seriously  maintain  that  a  thought  which 
belongs  to  an  ancient  sphere  of  mental  life  must  be  false  for  the 
very  reason  that  it  is  ancient? 

In  any  case,  it  is  fitting  that  we  define  more  closely  the  sense 
in  which  we  are  to  regard  forces  as  the  dynamic  intermediaries  of 
uniform  occurrence.  Force  cannot  be  given  as  a  content  of  perception 
either  through  our  senses  or  through  our  consciousness  of  self; 
in  the  case  of  the  former,  not  in  our  kinesthetic  sensations,  in  the 
case  of  the  latter,  not  in  our  consciousness  of  volition.  Volition 
would  not  include  a  consciousness  of  force,  even  though  we  were 
justified  in  regarding  it  as  a  simple  primitive  psychosis,  and  were  not 
compelled  rather  to  regard  it  as  an  intricate  collection  of  feelings 
and  sensations  as  far  as  these  elementary  forms  of  consciousness  are 
connected  in  thought  with  the  phenomena  of  reaction.  Again, 
forces  cannot  be  taken  as  objects  that  are  derived  as  possible  percep- 
tions or  after  the  analogy  of  possible  perceptions.  The  postulate  of 
our  thought  through  which  these  forces  are  derived  from  the  facts 
of  the  uniform  sequence  of  events,  reveals  them  as  limiting  notions 
(Grenzhegriffe) ,  as  specializations  of  the  necessary  connection  be- 
tween cause  and  effect,  or  of  the  real  dependence  of  the  former  upon 
the  latter;  for  the  manner  of  their  causal  intermediation  is  in  no  way 
given,  rather  they  can  be  thought  of  only  as  underlying  our  percep- 
tions. They  are  then  in  fact  qualitates  occultae ;  but  they  are  such 
only  because  the  concept  of  quality  is  taken  from  the  contents  of 
our  sense  and  self  perception,  which  of  course  do  not  contain  the 
necessary  connection  required  by  our  thought.  Whoever,  therefore, 
requires  from  the  introduction  of  forces  new  contents  of  percep- 
tion, for  instance,  new  and  fuller  mechanical  pictures,  expects  the 
impossible. 

The  contempt  with  which  the  assumption  of  forces  meets,  on 
the  part  of  those  who  make  this  demand,  is  accordingly  easily 
understood,  and  still  more  easily  is  it  understood,  if  one  takes  into 
consideration  what  confusion  of  concepts  has  arisen  through  the  use 
of  the  term  "force"  and  what  obstacles  the  assumption  of  forces  has 
put  in  the  way  of  the  material  sciences.  It  must  be  frankly  admitted 
that  this  concept  delayed  for  centuries  both  in  the  natural  and  moral 
sciences  the  necessary  analysis  of  the  complicated  phenomena 
forming  our  data.  Under  the  influence  of  the  "concept  philosophy  " 
it  caused,  over  and  over  again,  the  setting  aside  of  the  problems 
of  this  analytical  empirical  thought  as  soon  as  their  solution  had 
been  begun.   This  misuse  cannot  but  make  suspicious  from  the  very 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE   CAUSAL   LAW    385 

start  every  new  form  of  maintaining  that  forces  underlie  causa- 
tion. 

However,  misuse  proves  as  little  here  against  a  proper  use  as  it 
does  in  other  cases.  Moreover,  the  scruples  that  we  found  arising 
from  the  standpoint  of  empiricism  against  the  assumption  of  forces 
are  not  to  the  point.  In  assuming  a  dynamic  intermediary  between 
cause  and  effect,  we  are  not  doubling  the  problems  whose  solution  is 
incumbent  upon  the  sciences  of  facts,  and  still  less  is  it  true  that  our 
assumption  must  lead  to  a  logical  circle.  That  is,  a  comparison 
with  the  ideas  of  the  old  concept  philosophy,  which  even  in  the 
Aristotelian  doctrine  contain  such  a  duplication,  is  not  to  the  point. 
Those  ideas  are  hypostasized  abstractions  which  are  taken  from  the 
uniformly  coexisting  characteristics  of  objects.  Forces,  on  the  other 
hand,  are  the  imperceivable  relations  of  dependence  which  we  must 
presuppose  between  events  that  follow  one  another  uniformly,  if  the 
uniformity  of  this  sequence  is  to  become  for  us  either  thinkable  or 
conceivable.  The  problems  of  material  scientific  research  are  not 
doubled  by  this  presupposition  of  a  real  dynamic  dependence,  be- 
cause it  introduces  an  element  not  contained  in  the  data  of  percep- 
tion which  give  these  problems  their  point  of  departure.  This  pre- 
supposition does  not  renew  the  thought  of  an  analytic  rational 
connection  between  cause  and  effect  which  the  concept  philosophy 
involves;  on  the  contrary,  it  remains  true  to  the  principle  made 
practical  by  Hume  and  Kant,  that  the  real  connection  between 
causes  and  their  effects  is  determinable  only  through  experience, 
that  is,  empirically  and  synthetically  through  the  actual  indication 
of  the  events  of  uniform  sequence.  How  these  forces  are  constituted 
and  work,  we  cannot  know,  since  our  knowledge  is  confined  to  the 
material  of  perception  from  which  as  a  basis  presentation  has  de- 
veloped into  thought.  The  insight  that  we  have  won  from  the  limit- 
ing notion  of  force  helps  us  rather  to  avoid  the  misuse  which  has 
been  made  of  the  concept  of  force.  A  fatal  circle  first  arises,  when  we 
use  the  unknowable  forces  and  not  the  knowable  events  for  the 
purpose  of  explanation,  that  is,  when  we  cut  off  short  the  empirical 
analysis  which  leads  ad  infinitum.  To  explain  does  not  mean  to 
deduce  the  known  from  the  unknown,  but  the  particular  from  the 
general.  It  was  therefore  no  arbitrary  judgment,  but  an  impulse 
conditioned  by  the  very  nature  of  our  experience  and  of  our  thought, 
that  made  man  early  regard  the  causal  connection  as  a  dynamic 
one,  even  though  his  conception  was  of  course  indistinct  and  mixed 
with  confusing  additions. 

The  concept  of  force  remains  indispensable  also  for  natural  scien- 
tific thought.  It  is  involved  with  the  causal  law  in  every  attempt  to 
form  an  hypothesis,  and  accordingly  it  is  already  present  in  every 
description  of  facts  which  goes  by  means  of  memory  or  abstraction 


386  METHODOLOGY   OF  SCIENCE 

beyond  the  immediately  given  content  of  present  perception.  In 
introducing  it  we  have  in  mind,  moreover,  that  the  foundations  of 
every  possible  interpretation  of  nature  possess  a  dynamic  character, 
just  because  all  empirical  thought,  in  this  field  as  well,  is  subordinate 
to  the  causal  law.  This  must  be  admitted  by  any  one  who  assumes 
as  indispensable  aids  of  natural  science  the  mechanical  figures 
through  which  we  reduce  the  events  of  sense  perception  to  the  mo- 
tion of  mass  particles,  that  is,  through  which  we  associate  these 
events  with  the  elements  of  our  visual  and  tactual  perception.  All 
formulations  of  the  concept  of  mass,  even  when  they  are  made  so 
formal  as  in  the  definition  given  by  Heinrich  Hertz,  indicate  dynamic 
interpretations.  Whether  the  impelling  forces  are  to  be  thought  of 
in  particular  as  forces  acting  at  a  distance  or  as  forces  acting  through 
collision  depends  upon  the  answer  to  the  question  whether  we  have 
to  assume  the  dynamic  mass  particles  as  filling  space  discontinuously 
or  continuously.  The  dynamic  basis  of  our  interpretation  of  nature 
will  be  seen  at  once  by  any  one  who  is  of  the  opinion  that  we  can  make 
the  connection  of  events  intelligible  without  the  aid  of  mechanical 
figures",  for  instance,  in  terms  of  energy. 

Thus  it  results  that  we  interpret  the  events  following  one  another 
immediately  and  uniformly  as  causes  and  effects,  by  presupposing 
as  fundamental  to  them  forces  that  are  the  necessary  means  of  their 
uniformity  of  connection.  What  w^e  call  "laws"  are  the  judgments 
in  which  we  formulate  these  causal  connections. 

A  second  and  a  third  consequence  need  only  be  mentioned  here. 
The  hypothesis  that  interprets  the  mutual  connection  of  psychical 
and  physical  vital  phenomena  as  a  causal  one  is  as  old  as  it  is  natural. 
It  is  natural,  because  even  simple  observations  assure  us  that  the 
mental  content  of  perception  follows  uniformly  the  instigating 
physical  stimulus  and  the  muscular  movement  the  instigating 
mental  content  which  we  apprehend  as  will.  We  know,  however, 
that  the  physical  events  which,  in  raising  the  biological  problem,  we 
have  to  set  beside  the  psychical,  do  not  take  place  in  the  periphery  of 
our  nervous  system  and  in  our  muscles,  but  in  the  central  nervous 
system.  But  we  must  assume,  in  accordance  with  all  the  psycho- 
physiological data  which  at  the  present  time  are  at  our  disposal,  that 
these  events  in  our  central  nervous  system  do  not  follow  the  cor- 
responding psychical  events,  but  that  both  series  have  their  course 
simultaneously.  We  have  here,  therefore,  instead  of  the  real  relation 
of  dependence  involved  in  constant  sequence,  a  real  dependence  of 
the  simultaneity  or  correlative  series  of  events.  This  would  not,  of 
course,  as  should  be  at  once  remarked,  tell  as  such  against  a  causal 
connection  between  the  two  separate  causal  series.  But  the  contested 
paralielistic  interpretation  of  this  dependence  is  made  far  more 
probable  through  other  grounds.   These  are  in  part  corollaries  of  the 


i 


CONTENT  AND  VALIDITY  OF  THE   CAUSAL    LAW    387 

law  of  the  conservation  of  energy,  rightly  interpreted,  and  in  part 
epistemological  considerations.  Still  it  is  not  advisable  to  burden 
methodological  study,  for  instance,  the  theory  of  induction,  with. 
these  remote  problems;  and  on  that  account  it  is  better  for  our 
present  investigation  to  subordinate  the  psychological  interdepend- 
ences to  the  causal  ones  in  the  narrower  sense. 

The  final  consequence,  too,  that  forces  itself  upon  our  attention 
is  close  at  hand  in  the  preceding  discussion.  The  tradition  prevailing 
since  Hume,  together  T\dth  its  inherent  opposition  to  the  inter- 
pretation of  causal  connection  given  by  the  concept  philosophy, 
permitted  us  to  make  the  uniform  sequences  of  events  the  basis  of 
our  discussion.  In  so  doing,  however,  our  attention  had  to  be  called 
repeatedly  to  one  reservation.  In  fact,  onl}^  a  moment  ago,  in  allud- 
ing to  the  psychological  interdependences,  we  had  to  emphasize 
the  uniform  sequence.  Elsewhere  the  arguments  depended  upon 
the  uniformity  that  characterizes  this  sequence;  and  rightly,  for  the 
reduction  of  the  causal  relation  to  the  fundamental  relation  of  the 
sequence  of  events  is  mereh"  a  convenient  one  and  not  the  only  pos- 
sible one.  As  soon  as  we  regard  the  causal  connection,  along  -v^dth 
the  opposed  and  equal  reaction,  as  an  interconnection,  then  cause 
and  effect  become,  as  a  matter  of  principle,  simultaneous.  The  sep- 
aration of  interaction  from  causation  is  not  justifiable. 

In  other  ways  also  we  can  so  transform  every  causal  relation 
that  cause  and  effect  must  be  regarded  as  simultaneous.  Every 
stage,  for  instance,  of  the  warming  of  a  stone  by  the  heat  of  the 
sun,  or  of  the  treaty  conferences  of  two  states,  presents  an  effect 
that  is  simultaneous  with,  the  totality  of  the  acting  causes.  The 
analysis  of  a  cause  that  was  at  first  grasped  as  a  whole  into  the 
multiplicity  of  its  constituent  causes  and  the  comprehension  of 
the  constituent  causes  into  a  whole,  which  then  presents  itself  as 
the  effect,  is  a  necessarj^  condition  of  such  a  type  of  investigation. 
This  conception,  which  is  present  already  in  Hobbes,  but  especially 
in  Herbart's  '^nethod  of  relations,"  deserves  preference  always 
where  the  purpose  in  view  is  not  the  shortest  possible  argumentation 
but  the  most  exact  analysis. 

If  we  turn  our  attention  to  this  way  of  viewing  the  problem,  — 
not,  however,  in  the  form  of  Herbart's  speculative  method,  —  we 
shall  find  that  the  results  which  we  have  gained  will  in  no  respect  be 
altered.  We  do,  however,  get  a  view  bej^ond.  From  it  we  can  find 
the  way  to  subordinate  not  onh*  the  uniform  sequence  of  events, 
but  also  the  persistent  characteristics  and  states  with  their  mutual 
relations,  under  the  extended  causal  law.  In  so  doing,  we  do  not 
fall  back  again  into  the  intellectual  world  of  the  concept  philosophy. 
We  come  only  to  regard  the  persisting  coexistences  —  in  the  physical 
field,  the  bodies,  in  the  psychical,  the  subjects  of  consciousness  —  as 


388  METHODOLOGY  OF   SCIENCE 

systems  or  modes  of  activity.  The  thoughts  to  which  such  a  doctrine 
leads  are  accordingly  not  new  or  unheard  of.    The  substances  have 
always  been  regarded  as  sources  of  modes  of  activity.  We  have  here 
merely  new  modifications  of  thoughts  that  have  been  variously  de- 
veloped, not  only  from  the  side  of  empiricism,  but  also  from  that 
of  rationalism.   They  carry  with  them  methodologically  the  implica- 
tion that  it  is  possible  to  grasp  the  totality  of  reality,  as  far  as  it 
reveals  uniformities,  as  a  causally  connected  whole,  as  a  cosmos. 
They  give  the  research  of  the  special  sciences  the  conceptual  bases  for 
the  wider  prospects  that  the  sciences  of  facts  have  through  hard 
labor  won  for  themselves.   The  subject  of  consciousness  is  unitary  as 
far  as  the  processes  of  memory  extend,  but  it  is  not  simple.    On  the 
contrary,  it  is  most  intricately  put  together  out  of  psychical  com- 
plexes, themselves  intricate  and  out  of  their  relations;   all  of  which 
impress  upon  us,  psychologically  and,  in  their  mechanical  correlates, 
physiologically,  an  ever-recurring  need  for  further  empirical  analysis. 
Among  the  mechanical  images  of  physical  reality  that  form  the 
foundation  of  our  interpretation  of  nature,  there  can  finally  be  but 
one  that  meets  all  the  requirements  of  a  general  hypothesis  of  the 
continuity  of  kinetic  connections.     With  this  must  be  universally 
coordinated   the  persistent  properties  or  sensible  modes  of  action 
belonging  to  bodies.    The  mechanical  constitution  of  the  compound 
bodies,  no  matter  at  what  stage  of  combination  and  formation,  must 
be  derivable  from  the  mechanical  constitution  of  the  elements  of  this 
combination.     Thus  our  causal  thought  compels  us  to  trace  back 
the  persistent  coexistences   of   the  so-called  elements  to  combin- 
ations whose  analysis,  as  yet  hardly  begun,  leads  us  on  likewise  to 
indefinitely  manifold  problems.    Epistemologically  we  come  finally 
to    a  universal  phenomenological  dynamism  as  the  fundamental 
basis  of  all  theoretical  interpretation  of  the  world,  at  least  funda- 
mental for  our  scientific  thought,  and  we  are  here  concerned  with 
no  other. 


SECTION  E  — ETHICS 


SECTION  E  — ETHICS 


{Hall  6,  September  23,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:  Professor  George  H.  Palmer,  Harvard  University. 
Speakers:   Professor  William  R.  Sorley,  University  of  Cambridge. 
Professor  Paul  Hensel,  University  of  Erlangen. 
Secretary:  Professor  F.  C.  Sharp,  University  of  Wisconsin. 


THE   RELATIONS   OF   ETHICS 

BY    WILLIAM   RITCHIE    SORLEY 

[William  Ritchie  Sorley,  Knightbridge  Professor  of  Moral  Philosophy  in  the 
University  of  Cambridge;  Fellow  of  the  British  Academy .  b.  Sellcirk,  Scot- 
land, 1855.  M.A.  Edinburgh;  Litt.D.  Cambridge;  Hon.  LL.D.  Edinburgh. 
Post-Graduate,  Shaw  Fellow,  Edinburgh  University,  1878;  Fellow,  Trinity 
College,  Cambridge,  1883;  Lecturer,  Local  Lectures  Syndicate  and  for  the 
Moral  Science  Board,  Cambridge,  1882-86;  Deputy  for  the  Professor  of 
Philosophy,  University  College,  London,  1886-87;  Prof essor  of  Philosophy, 
University  College,  Cardiff,  1888-94;  Regius  Professor  Moral  Philosophy, 
Aberdeen,  1894-1900.  Author  of  Ethics  of  Naturalism,  1885  (new  ed.  1904); 
Mining  Royalties,  1889;  Recent  Tendencies  in  Ethics,  1904;  Edition  of 
Adam^on  Development  of  Modern  Philosophy,  1903.] 

There  are  many  departments  of  inquiry  whose  scope  is  so  well 
defined  by  the  consensus  of  experts  that  one  may  proceed,  almost 
without  preliminary,  to  mark  off  the  boundaries  of  one  science  from 
other  departments,  to  investigate  the  relations  in  which  it  stands 
to  them,  and  to  exhibit  the  place  which  each  occupies  in  the  whole 
scheme  of  human  knowledge.  In  other  departments  opinion  differs 
not  only  regarding  special  problems  and  results,  but  concerning  the 
whole  nature  of  the  science  and  its  relation  to  connected  subjects. 
The  study  of  ethics  still  belongs  to  this  latter  group.  In  it  there  is  no 
consensus  of  experts.  Competent  scholars  hold  diametrically  opposed 
views  as  to  its  scope.  They  differ  not  merely  in  the  answers  they 
give  to  ethical  questions,  but  in  their  views  as  to  what  the  fundamen- 
tal question  of  ethics  is.  And  this  opposition  of  opinion  as  to  its 
nature  is  connected  with  a  difference  of  view  regarding  the  relation 
of  ethics  to  the  sciences.  By  many  investigators  it  is  set  in  line 
with  the  sciences  of  biology,  psychology,  and  sociology;  and  its 
problems  are  formulated  and  discussed  by  the  application  of  the  same 
historical  method  as  those  sciences  employ.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is 
maintained  that  ethics  implies  and  requires  a  concept  so  different 
from  the  concepts  used  by  the  historical  and  natural  sciences  as  to 
give  its  problem  an  altogether  distinct  character  and  to  indicate 


392  ETHICS 

for  it  a  far  more  significant  position  in  the  whole  scheme  of  human 
thought. 

The  question  of  the  relation  of  ethics  to  the  sciences  implies  a  view 
of  the  nature  of  ethics  itself  and,  in  particular,  of  the  fundamental 
concept  used  in  ethical  judgments.  If  the  nature  of  this  concept  and 
its  relation  to  the  concepts  employed  in  other  branches  of  inquiry 
can  be  determined,  the  relations  of  ethics  will  become  clear  of  them- 
selves. The  problem  of  this  paper  will  receive  its  most  adequate 
solution  —  so  far  as  the  time  at  my  disposal  permits  —  by  an  in- 
dependent inquiry  into  the  nature  of  the  ethical  concept  in  relation 
to  the  concepts  used  in  other  sciences. 

The  immediate  judgments  of  .experience  fall  into  two  broadly 
contrasted  classes,  which  may  be  described  in  brief  as  judgments 
of  fact  and  judgments  of  worth.  The  former  are  the  foundations 
on  which  the  whole  edifice  of  science  (as  the  term  is  commonly  used) 
is  built.  Science  has  no  other  object  than  to  understand  the  relations 
of  facts  as  exhibited  in  historical  sequence,  in  causal  interconnection, 
or  in  the  logical  interdependence  which  may  be  discovered  amongst 
their  various  aspects.  In  its  beginnings  it  may  have  arisen  as  an  aid 
to  the  attainment  of  practical  purposes:  it  is  still  everywhere  yoked 
to  the  chariot  of  man's  desires  and  aims.  But  it  has  for  long 
vindicated  an  independent  position  for  itself.  It  may  be  turned  to 
what  uses  you  will;  but  its  essential  spirit  stands  aloof  from  these 
uses.  It  has  one  interest  only,  —  to  know  what  happens  and  how. 
Otherwise  it  is  indifferent  to  all  purposes  alike.  It  studies  with 
equal  mind  the  slow  growth  of  a  plant  or  the  swift  destruction 
wrought  by  the  torpedo,  the  reign  of  a  Caligula  or  of  a  Victoria;  it 
takes  no  side,  but  observes  and  describes  all  "  just  as  if  the  question 
were  of  lines,  planes,  and  solids."  Mathematical  method  does  not 
limit  its  range,  but  it  typifies  its  attitude  of  indifference  to  every 
interest  save  one,  —  that  of  knowing  the  what  and  how  of  things. 

We  can  conceive  an  intelligence  of  this  nature,  a  pure  intelligence, 
or  mere  intelligence,  to  whose  understanding  all  the  relations  of 
things  are  evident,  with  the  prophetic  power  of  the  Laplacian  Demon 
and  the  gift  of  tongues  to  make  its  knowledge  clear,  and  yet  unable  to 
distinguish  between  good  and  evil  or  to  see  beauty  or  ugliness  in 
nature.  We  can  conceive  such  an  intelligence;  but  it  is  an  unreality, 
a  mere  abstraction  from  the  scientific  aspect  of  human  intelligence. 
Pure  intelligence  of  this  sort  does  not  exist  in  man,  and  we  have  no 
grounds  for  asserting  its  existence  anywhere.  In  the  experience 
which  forms  the  basis  of  mental  life,  judgments  of  reality  are  every- 
where combined  with  and  colored  by  judgments  of  worth.  And  the 
latter  are  as  insistent  as  the  former,  and  make  up  as  large  a  part  of 
our  experience.  If  we  go  back  to  the  original  judgments  of  experi- 
ence, we  find  that  they  are  not  only  of  the  form  "  it  is  here  or  there," 


THE  RELATIONS   OF   ETHICS  393 

"it  is  of  this  nature  or  that,"  "it  has  such  and  such  effects;"  just 
as  a  large  part  of  our  experience  is  of  another  order  which  may  be 
expressed  in  judgments  of  the  form  "it  is  good  or  evil/'  "it  is  fair  or 
foul." 

Nor  does  the  way  in  which  scientific  judgments  are  elaborated 
give  any  rationale  of  the  distinction  between  good  and  evil.  If  we 
ask  of  science  "What  is  good?"  it  can  give  no  relevant  answer  to  the 
question.  Strictly  speaking,  it  does  not  understand  the  meaning  of 
the  question  at  all.  The  ball  has  gone  out  of  bounds;  and  science  can- 
not touch  it  until  it  has  been  thrown  back  into  the  field.  It  can  say 
what  is,  and  what  will  happen,  and  it  can  describe  the  methods  or 
laws  by  which  things  come  to  pass;  that  is  all;  it  has  only  one  law 
for  the  just  and  the  unjust. 

But  science  is  very  resourceful,  and  is  able  to  deal  with  judgments 
of  worth  from  its  own  point  of  view.  For  these  judgments  also  are 
facts  of  individual  experience:  they  are  formed  by  human  minds 
under  certain  conditions,  betray  certain  relations  to  the  judgments 
of  fact  with  which  they  are  associated,  and  are  connected  with  an 
environment  of  social  institutions  and  physical  conditions  of  life: 
they  have  a  history  therefore.  And  in  these  respects  they  become 
part  of  the  material  for  science:  and  a  description  of  them  can  be 
given  by  psychological  and  historical  methods. 

The  general  nature  and  results  of  the  application  of  these  methods 
to  ethics  are  too  well  known  to  need  further  comment,  too  well  estab- 
lished to  require  defense.  But  these  results  may  be  exaggerated  and 
have  been  exaggerated.  When  all  has  been  said  and  done  that  the 
historical  method  can  say  and  do,  the  question  "What  is  good?" 
is  found  to  remain  exactly  where  it  was.  We  may  have  learned  much 
as  to  the  way  in  which  certain  kinds  of  conduct  in  certain  circum- 
stances promote  certain  ends,  and  as  to  the  gradual  changes  which 
men's  ideas  about  good  and  evil,  virtue  and  vice,  have  passed  through; 
but  we  have  not  touched  the  fundamental  question  which  ethics  has 
to  face  —  the  question  of  the  nature  of  worth  or  goodness  or  duty. 
And  yet  it  is  this  question  only  which  gives  significance  to  the 
problems  on  which  historical  evolution  has  been  able  to  throw  light. 
Moral  ideas  and  moral  institutions  have  all  along  been  effective 
factors  in  human  development,  as  well  as  the  subject  of  development 
themselves.  And  the  secret  of  their  power  has  lain  in  this  that  men 
have  believed  in  those  ideas  as  expressing  a  moral  imperative  or  a 
moral  end,  and  that  they  have  looked  upon  moral  institutions  as 
embodiments  of  something  which  has  worth  for  man  or  a  moral 
claim  upon  his  devotion.  These  ideas  and  institutions  would  have 
had  no  power  apart  from  this  belief  in  their  validity. 

But  was  this  belief  true?    Were  the  ideas  or  institutions  valid? 
This  question  the  man  of  science,  as  sociologist  or  historian,  does  not 


394  ETHICS 

answer  and  has  no  means  of  answering.  He  can  show  their  adapta- 
tion or  want  of  adaptation  to  certain  ends,  but  he  can  say  nothing 
about  the  vaUdity  of  these  ends  themselves.  It  is  implied  in  their 
efficiency  that  these  ends  were  conceived  as  having  moral  value  or 
moral  authority.  But  to  what  ends  does  this  moral  value  or  authority 
truly  belong?  and  what  is  its  significance?  —  these  are  questions 
which  the  positive  sciences  (such  as  psychology  and  sociology)  can- 
not touch  and  which  must  be  answered  by  other  methods  than  those 
which  they  employ. 

The  moral  concept  is  expressed  in  various  ways  and  by  a  variety 
of  terms,  —  right,  duty,  merit,  virtue,  goodness,  worth.  And  these 
different  terms  indicate  different  aspects  opened  up  by  a  single  new 
point  of  view.  Thus  "  right '^  seems  to  imply  correspondence  with  a 
standard  or  rule,  which  standard  or  rule  is  some  moral  law  or  ideal 
of  goodness;  and  "merit"  indicates  performance  of  the  right, 
perhaps  in  victory  over  some  conflicting  desire;  and  "virtue"  means 
a  trait  of  character  in  which  performance  of  this  sort  has  become 
habitual.  The  term  "worth"  has  conveniences  which  have  led  to 
its  having  considerable  vogue  in  ethical  treatises  since  the  time  of 
Herbart;  it  lends  itself  easily  to  psychological  manipulation;  but 
it  does  not  seem  to  refer  to  a  concept  fundamentally  distinct  from 
goodness.  But  between  "goodness"  and  "duty"  there  seems  to  be 
this  difference  at  any  rate,  that  the  latter  term  refers  definitely  to 
something  to  be  done  by  a  voluntary  agent,  whereas,  in  calling  some- 
thing "good,"  we  may  have  no  thought  of  action  at  all,  but  only 
see  and  name  a  quality. 

There  lies  here  therefore  a  difference  which  is  not  a  mere  difference 
of  expression. 

On  the  one  hand  it  may  be  held  that  good  is  a  quality  which  be- 
longs to  certain  things  and  has  no  special  and  immediate  reference 
to  volition:  that  we  say  this  or  that  is  good  as  we  say  that  some- 
thing else  is  heavy  or  green  or  positively  electrified.  No  relation  to 
human  life  at  all  may  be  implied  in  the  one  form  of  judgment  any 
more  than  in  the  other.  That  relation  will  only  follow  by  way  of 
application  to  circumstances.  Just  as  a  piece  of  lead  may  serve  as 
a  letter-weight  because  it  is  heavy,  so  certain  actions  may  come  to 
be  our  duty  because  they  lead  to  the  realization  of  something  which 
is  objectively  good  in  quality. 

According  to  the  other  view  goodness  has  reference  in  its  primary 
meaning  to  free  self-conscious  agency.  The  good  is  that  which 
ought  to  be  brought  into  existence:  goodness  is  a  quality  of  things, 
but  only  in  a  derivative  regard  because  these  things  are  produced 
by  a  good  will.  It  is  objective,  too,  inasmuch  as  it  unites  the  individual 
will  with  a  law  or  ideal  which  has  a  claim  upon  the  will;  but  it  does 
not  in  its  primary  meaning  indicate  something  out  of  relation  to  the 


THE   RELATIONS   OF   ETHICS  395 

will:  if  there  were  no  will  there  would  be  no  law;   apart  from  con- 
scious agency  good  and  evil  would  disappear. 

The  question  thus  raised  is  one  of  real  and  fundamental  import- 
ance. "Ethics"  by  its  very  name  may  seem  to  have  primary  refer- 
ence to  conduct;  and  that  is  the  view  which  most  moralists  have, 
in  one  way  or  another,  adopted.  But  the  other  view  which  gives  to 
the  concept  "good"  an  independence  of  all  relation  to  volition  is  not 
always  definitely  excluded,  even  by  these  moralists;  by  others  it 
has  been  definitely  maintained:  it  seems  implied  in  Plato's  idealism, 
at  one  stage  of  its  development;  and  quite  recently  a  doctrine  of 
the  principles  of  ethics  has  been  worked  out  which  is  based  on  its 
explicit  recognition.^ 

If  we  would  attempt  to  decide  between  these  two  conflicting 
views  of  the  ethical  concept,  we  must,  in  the  first  place,  imitate  the 
procedure  of  science  and  examine  the  facts  on  which  the  concept 
is  based.  To  get  to  the  meaning  of  such  scientific  concepts  as  "mass," 
"energy,"  or  the  like,  we  begin  by  a  consideration  of  the  facts  which 
the  concepts  are  introduced  to  describe.  These  facts  are  in  the  last 
resort  the  objects  of  sense  perception.  No  examination  of  these 
sense  percepts  will,  as  we  have  seen,,  yield  the  content  of  the  ethical 
concept;  good  and  evil  are  not  given  in  sense  perception — they  are 
themselves  an  estimate  of,  or  way  of  regarding,  the  immediate 
material  of  experience.  Moral  experience  is  thus  in  a  manner  reflex, 
as  so  many  of  the  English  moralists  have  called  it.  Its  attitude  to 
things  is  not  merely  receptive;  and  the  concepts  to  which  it  gives 
rise  have  not  mere  understanding  in  view.  Objects  are  perceived  as 
they  occur;  and  experience  of  them  is  the  groundwork  of  science. 
There  is  also,  at  the  same  time,  an  attitude  of  approbation  or  dis- 
approbation; this  attitude  is  the  special  characteristic  of  moral 
experience;  and  from  moral  experience  the  ethical  concept  is  formed. 

This  reflex  experience,  or  reflex  attitude  to  experience,  is  exhibited 
in  different  ways.  There  is,  to  begin  with,  the  appreciation  of  beauty 
in  its  various  kinds  and  degrees  and  the  corresponding  depreciation 
of  ugliness  or  deformity.  These  give  rise  to  the  concepts  and  judg- 
ments of  aesthetics.  They  are  closely  related  to  moral  approbation 
and  disapprobation,  so  closely  that  there  has  always  been  a  tendency 
amongst  a  school  of  moralists  to  strain  the  facts  by  identifying  them. 
A  certain  looseness  in  our  use  of  terms  favors  this  tendency.  For 
we  do  often  use  good  of  a  work  of  art  or  even  scene  in  nature  when 
we  mean  beautiful.  But  if  we  reflect  on  and  compare  our  mental 
attitudes  in  commending,  say,  a  sunset  and  self-sacrifice,  it  seems 
to  me  that  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  the  two  attitudes  are  different. 
Both  objects  may  be  admired;  but  both  are  not,  in  the  same  sense, 
approved.    It  is  hard  to  express  this  difference  otherwise  than  by 

1  Prindpia  Ethica,  by  G.  E.  Moore  (1903). 


398  ETHICS 

saying  that  the  moral  attitude  is  present  in  the  one  and  absent  in  the 
other.  But  the  difference  is  brought  out  by  the  fact  that  our  sesthet- 
ical  and  moral  attitudes  towards  the  same  experience  may  diverge 
from  one  another.  We  may  admire  the  beauty  of  that  which  we 
condemn  as  immoral.  De  Quincey  saw  a  fine  art  in  certain  cases 
of  murder;  the  finish  and  perfection  of  wickedness  may  often  stir 
a  certain  artistic  admiration,  especially  if  we  lull  the  moral  sense  to 
sleep.  And,  on  the  other  hand,  moral  approval  is  often  tempered 
by  a  certain  aesthetic  depreciation  of  those  noble  characters  who  do 
good  awkwardly,  without  the  ease  and  grace  of  a  gentleman.  John 
Knox  and  Mary  Queen  of  Scots  (if  I  may  assume  for  the  moment 
an  historical  judgment  which  may  need  qualification)  will  each  have 
his  or  her  admirers  according  as  the  moral  or  sesthetic  attitude 
preponderates  —  the  harsh  tones  of  the  one  appealing  to  the  law 
of  truth  and  goodness,  the  other  an  embodiment  of  the  beauty  and 
gaiety  of  life,  "without  a  moral  sense,  however  feeble." 

Nor  is  sesthetic  appreciation  the  only  other  reflex  attitude  which 
has  a  place  in  our  experience  side  by  side  with  the  moral.  Judgments 
about  matters  of  fact  and  relations  of  ideas  are  discriminated  as 
true  or  false;  an  ideal  of  truth  is  formed;  and  conditions  of  its 
realization  are  laid  down.  Here  again  we  have  a  concept  and  class 
of  judgments  analogous  to  our  sesthetical  and  ethical  concepts  and 
judgments,  but  not  the  same  as  them,  and  not  likely  to  be  confused 
with  them. 

Beside  these  may  be  put  a  whole  class  of  judgments  of  worth 
which  may  be  described  as  judgments  of  utiUty.  We  estimate  and 
approve  or  disapprove  various  facts  of  experience  according  to  their 
tendency  to  promote  or  interfere  with  certain  ends  or  objects  of 
desire.  That  moral  judgments  are  to  be  identified  with  a  special 
class  of  these  judgments  of  utility  is  a  thesis  too  well  known  to 
require  discussion  here,  and  too  important  to  admit  of  discussion  in 
a  few  words.  But  it  may  be  pointed  out  that  it  is  only  in  a  very 
special  and  restricted  sense  of  the  term  "utility"  that  judgments 
of  utility  have  ever  been  identified  with  moral  judgments.  The 
"  jimmy  "  is  useful  to  the  burglar,  as  his  instruments  are  useful  to 
the  surgeon;  and  they  are  in  both  cases  appreciated  by  the  same 
kind  of  reflective  judgment.  Judgments  of  utility  are  all  of  them, 
properly  speaking,  judgments  about  means  to  ends;  and  the  ends 
may  and  do  differ;  while  it  is  only  by  a  forced  interpretation  that  aU 
these  ends  are  sometimes  and  somehow  made  to  resolve  themselves 
into  pleasure. 

It  is  enough,  however,  for  my  present  purpose  to  recognize  the 
prima  fade  distinction  of  moral  judgments  or  judgments  of  goodness 
from  other  judgments  of  worth,  such  as  those  of  utility,  of  beauty, 
and  of  truth  (in  the  sense  in  which  these  last  also  are  judgments  of 


THE  RELATIONS   OF   ETHICS  397 

worth).  Had  the  question  of  the  origin  and  history  of  the  moral 
judgment  been  before  us,  a  great  deal  more  might  have  been  neces- 
sary. For  our  present  purpose  what  has  been  already  said  may  be 
sufficient:  it  was  required  in  order  to  enable  us  to  approach  the 
consideration  of  the  question  already  raised  concerning  the  applica- 
tion and  meaning  of  the  moral  concept. 

The  question  is,  Does  our  moral  experience  support  the  assignment 
of  the  predicate  "good"  or  "bad"  to  things  regarded  as  quite  inde- 
pendent of  volition  or  consciousness?  At  first  sight  it  may  seem 
easy  to  answer  the  question  in  the  affirmative.  We  do  talk  of  sun- 
shine and  gentle  rain  and  fertile  land  as  good,  and  of  tornadoes  and 
disease  and  death  as  bad.  But  I  think  that  when  we  do  so,  in  nine 
cases  out  of  ten,  our  "good"  or  "bad"  is  not  a  moral  good  or 
bad;  they  are  predicates  of  utility  or  sometimes  sesthetic  predicates, 
not  moral  predicates;  and  we  recognize  this  in  recognizing  their 
relativity:  the  fertile  land  is  called  good  because  its  fertility  makes 
it  useful  to  man's  primary  needs;  but  the  barren  and  rocky  moun- 
tain may  be  better  in  the  eyes  of  the  tourist,  though  the  farmer 
would  call  it  bad  land.  There  is  an  appreciation,  a  judgment  of 
worth  in  the  most  general  sense,  in  such  experiences;  but  they  are 
in  most  cases  without  the  special  feature  of  moral  approbation  or 
disapprobation. 

There  remains,  however,  the  tenth  case  in  which  the  moral  predi- 
cate does  seem  to  be  applied  to  the  unconscious.  One  may  instance 
J.  S.  Mill's  passionate  impeachment  of  the  course  of  nature,  in  which 
"habitual  injustice"  and  "nearly  all  the  things  which  men  are 
hanged  or  imprisoned  for  doing  to  one  another"  are  spoken  of  as 
"nature's  every-day  performances;"^  and  a  similar  indictment 
was  brought  by  Professor  Huxley,  twenty  years  after  the  publica- 
tion of  Mill's  essay,  against  the  cosmic  process  for  its  encourage- 
ment of  selfishness  and  ferocity.^  These  are  only  examples.  Litera- 
ture is  full  of  similar  reflections  on  the  indiscriminate  slaughter 
wrought  by  the  earthquake  or  the  hurricane,  and  on  the  sight  of  the 
wicked  flourishing  or  of  the  righteous  begging  his  bread;  and  these 
reflections  find  an  echo  in  the  experience  of  most  men. 

But  the  nature  of  this  experience  calls  for  remark. 

In  the  first  place,  if  we  look  more  closely  at  the  arguments  of  Mill 
or  Huxley,  we  see  that  both  are  cases  of  criticism  of  a  philosophical 
theory.  Mill  was  refuting  a  view  which  he  held  (and  rightly  held) 
to  have  influence  still  on  popular  thought,  though  it  might  have 
ceased  to  be  a  living  ethical  theory  —  the  doctrine  that  the  standard 
of  right  and  wrong  was  to  be  found  in  nature;  it  was  in  keeping 
with  his  purpose,  therefore,  to  speak  of  the  operations  of  nature  as 

1  J.  S.  Mill,  Three  Essays  on  Religion,  pp.  35,  38. 

^  T.  H.  Huxley,  Evolution  and  Ethics  (Romanes  Lecture). 


398  ETHICS 

if  they  were  properly  the  subject  of  moral  praise  or  blame.  In  the 
same  way,  when  Huxley  wrote,  the  old  doctrine  which  Mill  regarded 
as  philosophically  extinct  and  only  surviving  as  a  popular  error  had 
been  revived  by  the  impetus  which  the  theory  of  evolution  had 
given  to  every  branch  of  study;  and  Huxley  was  criticising  the  evo- 
lutionist ethics  of  Spencer  and  others  who  looked  for  moral  guidance 
to  the  course  of  evolution.  He,  therefore,  was  led  to  speak  of  the 
cosmic  process  as  a  possible  subject  of  moral  predicates,  not  neces- 
sarily because  he  thought  that  application  appropriate,  but  in  order 
to  demonstrate  the  hollowness  of  the  ethics  of  evolution  by  showing 
that  if  the  moral  predicate  could  be  applied  at  all,  then  the  appro- 
priate adjective  would  be  not  "good"  but  "bad." 

Perhaps  there  is  more  than  this  in  Huxley;  and  Mill's  expressions 
often  betray  a  direct  and  genuine  moral  condemnation  of  the  methods 
of  nature  as  methods  of  wickedness;  and,  still  more  clearly,  this 
immediate  moral  disapproval  may  be  found  in  expressions  of  common 
experience  as  yet  uncolored  by  philosophy.  But  if  we  examine  these 
we  find  that,  while  there  is  no  reference  to  philosophical  theories 
about  nature,  the  things  approved  or  condemned  are  yet  looked  upon 
as  implying  consciousness.  In  the  lower  stages  of  development  this 
implication  is  simply  animistic;  at  a  later  period  it  becomes  theo- 
logical. But  throughout  experience  moral  judgments  upon  nature  are 
not  passed  upon  mere  nature.  Its  forces  are  regarded  as  expressing  a 
purpose  or  mind;  and  it  is  this  that  is  condemned  or  approved.  The 
primitive  man  and  the  child  do  not  merely  condemn  the  misdoings  of 
inanimate  objects;  they  wreak  their  vengeance  upon  them  or  punish 
them :  and  this  is  a  consequence  of  their  animistic  interpretation  of 
natural  forces.  Gradually,  in  the  mental  growth  of  the  child,  this  ani- 
mistic interpretation  of  things  gives  place  to  an  understanding  of  the 
natural  laws  of  their  working;  and  at  the  same  time  and  by  the  same 
degrees,  the  child  ceases  to  inflict  punishment  upon  the  chair  that 
has  fallen  on  him  or  to  condemn  its  misdemeanor.  Here  the  moral 
judgment  is  displaced  by  the  causal  judgment;  and  the  reason  of  its 
displacement  is  the  disappearance  of  mind  or  purpose  from  amongst 
the  phenomena.  When  the  child  comes  to  understand  that  the 
chair  falls  by  "laws  of  nature"  which  are  not  the  expression  of  will, 
like  the  acts  done  by  himself  or  his  companions,  he  ceases  to  disap- 
prove or  to  resent,  though  he  does  not  cease  to  feel  pain  or  to  im- 
prove the  circumstances  by  setting  the  chair  firmly  on  the  floor. 
The  recognition  of  natural  causation  as  all  that  there  is  in  the  case 
leaves  no  room  for  the  moral  attitude.  So  true  is  this  that  the  same 
result  is  sometimes  thought  to  be  a  consequence  of  the  scientific 
understanding  even  of  what  is  called  moral  causation,  "tout  com- 
prendre  c'est  tout  pardonner  "  —  as  if  knowledge  of  motive  and  cir- 
cumstances were  sufficient  to  dispense  with  praise  or  blame. 


THE   RELATIONS   OF   ETHICS  399 

Moral  judgments  of  a  more  mature  kind  on  the  constitution  and 
course  of  nature  form  the  material  for  optimistic  and  pessimistic 
views  of  the  world  —  at  least,  when  these  views  rise  above  the  asser- 
tion of  a  preponderance  of  pleasure  or  of  pain  in  life.  But,  so  far  as 
I  can  see,  in  such  moral  judgments  nature  is  never  looked  upon  as 
consisting  of  dead  mechanical  sequences.  It  is  because  it  is  looked 
upon  as  the  expression  of  a  living  will  or  as  in  some  way  —  perhaps 
very  vaguely  conceived  — animated  by  purpose  or  consciousness,  that 
we  regard  it  as  morally  good  or  evil.  Apart  from  some  such  theological 
conception,  it  does  not  seem  to  me  that  the  nature  of  things  calls  out 
the  attitude  of  moral  approval  or  disapproval.  Things  are  estimated 
as  useful  for  this  or  that  end,  they  are  seen  and  appreciated  as 
beautiful  or  the  reverse,  without  any  reference  to  them  as  due  to  an 
inspiring  or  originating  mind;  and  in  one  or  other  of  these  references 
the  terms  "good"  or  "bad"  may  be  used.  But  when  we  use  the 
term  good  in  its  specifically  moral  signification,  we  do  not  apply 
it  to  the  inanimate,  except  in  a  derivate  way,  on  account  of  the 
relation  in  which  these  inanimate  things  stand  to  the  moral  ends 
and  character  of  conscious  beings. 

So  far,  therefore,  as  the  evidence  of  moral  experience  goes,  it 
does  not  support  the  view  that  the  "good"  is  a  quality  which  be- 
longs to  things  out  of  relation  to  self-conscious  activity.  And,  in  so 
far,  the  peculiarity  of  the  moral  experience  would  seem  to  be  better 
brought  out  by  the  conception  "ought"  than  by  the  conception 
"good." 

But  here  a  difficulty  arises  at  once.  For  how  can  we  say  that  any- 
thing ought  to  be  done  or  to  be  except  on  the  assumption  that  it  is 
antecedently  good?  Is  not  such  antecedent  and  independent  good- 
ness necessary  in  order  to  justify  the  assertion  that  any  one  ought 
to  produce  it? 

The  question  undoubtedly  points  to  a  difficulty;  and  if  that  diffi- 
culty can  be  solved  it  may  help  to  bring  out  the  true  significance  of 
the  moral  concept.  The  judgment  which  assigns  the  duty  of  an  indi- 
vidual —  according  to  which  I  or  any  one  ought  to  adopt  a  certain 
course  of  action  —  involves  a  special  application  of  the  moral  con- 
cept. It  binds  the  individual  to  a  certain  objective  rule  or  end.  The 
individual's  desires  as  mere  facts  of  experience  may  point  in  an 
altogether  different  direction;  the  purpose  or  volition  contemplated 
and  approved  by  the  moral  judgment  has  in  view  the  union  of  indi- 
vidual striving  with  an  end  which  is  objective  and,  as  objective,  uni- 
versal. This  union  involves  an  adaptation  of  two  things  which  may 
fall  asunder,  and  which  in  every  case  of  evil  volition  do  fall  asunder. 
And  the  adaptation  may  be  regarded  from  either  side:  on  the  side 
of  the  individual,  application  to  his  individuality  is  implied;  the 
duty  of  one  man  is  not  just  the  same  as  the  duty  of  any  other;  he 


400  ETHICS 

has  his  own  special  place  and  calling.  But  he  is  connected  with 
a  larger  purpose  which  in  his  consciousness  becomes  both  an  ideal 
and  a  law,  while  its  application  is  not  limited  to  his  individuality  or 
his  circumstances. 

All  this  is  implied  in  the  moral  judgment.  It  is  not  limited  to  one 
individual  consciousness  or  volition.  But  it  does  not  follow  that  the 
predicate  "good,"  in  the  ethical  meaning  of  the  term,  is  or  can  be 
applied  out  of  relation  to  consciousness  altogether.  At  the  earliest 
stages  of  moral  development  we  find  it  applied  unhesitatingly 
wherever  conscious  activity  is  supposed  to  be  present  —  to  anything 
that  is  regarded  as  the  embodiment  of  spirit;  and  it  is  applied  to  the 
universe  as  a  whole  when  the  universe  is  thought  of  as  the  product 
of  mind.  "  Good  "  is  not  even  limited  to  an  actual  existent;  it  neither 
implies  nor  denies  actual  existence.  "Such  and  such,  if  it  existed, 
would  be  a  good"  is  as  legitimate  though  not  so  primitive  an  expres- 
sion of  the  moral  judgment  as  "this  existent  is  good."  But  it  does 
imply  a  relation  to  existence.  It  does  not  even  seem  possible  to 
distinguish  except  verbally  between  "good"  and  "ought  to  be." 
And  this  "ought"  seems  to  imply  a  reference  to  a  purpose  through 
which  the  idea  is  to  be  realized. 

This  conception  "ought  to  be"  is  not  the  same  as  the  concept 
"ought  to  be  done  by  me."  The  latter  is  an  application  of  the  more 
general  concept  to  a  special  individual  in  special  circumstances; 
and  this  is  the  common  meaning  of  the  concept  duty.  The  former 
is  the  more  general  concept  of  "goodness."  It  may  be  called  object- 
ive, because  it  does  not  refer  to  any  individual  state  of  mind;  it  is 
universal  because  independent  of  the  judgments  and  desires  of  the 
individual;  and  when  the  goodness  is  not  due  to  its  tendency  towards 
some  further  end,  it  may  also  be  called  absolute. 

The  point  of  the  whole  argument  can  thus  be  made  clear  if  we 
bear  in  mind  the  familiar  distinction  between  "good  in  itself"  and 
"good  for  me  now."  That  the  latter  has  always  a  relation  to  con- 
sciousness is  obvious:  it  is  something  to  be  done  or  experienced  by 
me.  But  there  must  be  some  ground  why  anything  is  to  be  or  ought 
to  be  done  or  experienced  by  me  at  any  time.  Present  individual 
activity  must  rest  upon  or  be  connected  with  some  wider  or  objective 
basis.  What  is  good  for  me  points  to  and  depends  upon  something 
which  is  not  merely  relatively  good,  but  good  in  itself  or  absolutely. 
Yet  it  does  not  follow  that  this  good  in  itself  is  necessarily  absolute 
in  the  sense  of  having  significance  apart  altogether  from  conscious- 
ness. Its  absoluteness  consists  in  independence  of  individual  con- 
sciousness or  feeling,  not  in  independence  of  consciousness  altogether. 
It  is  objective  rather  than  absolute  in  the  literal  sense  of  the  term. 
The  good  in  itself,  like  the  relative  good,  is  one  aspect  which  can  only 
belong  to  a  consciousness  —  to  purpose.     The  moral  judgment  on 


THE  RELATIONS   OF   ETHICS  401 

things  —  either  on  the  universe  as  a  whole,  or  on  anything  in  the 
universe  which  is  not  regarded  as  due  to  the  will  of  man  —  is  only- 
Justified  if  we  regard  these  things  as  in  some  way  expressing  con- 
sciousness; either  as  directly  due  to  it,  or  as  aiding  it,  or  as  in  con- 
flict with  it.  From  any  other  point  of  view,  to  speak  of  things  as  good 
or  evil  (unless  in  some  non-ethical  sense  of  these  terms)  seems  out 
of  place,  and  is  unsupported  by  the  mode  of  application  which  be- 
longs to  the  immediate  judgments  of  the  moral  consciousness.  If 
the  moral  concept  has  significance  beyond  the  range  of  the  feelings 
and  desires  of  men,  it  is  because  the  objects  to  which  it  applies  are 
the  expression  of  mind. 

This  is  not  put  forward  as  a  vindication  of  a  spiritual  idealism. 
It  is  only  a  small  contribution  towards  the  meaning  of  "good."  A 
comprehensive  idealism  may  not  be  the  only  view  of  reality  with 
which  the  conclusions  reached  so  far  will  harmonize.  But  it  is  the 
view  with  which  they  harmonize  most  simply.  The  conception  of  a 
purpose  to  which  all  the  events  of  the  world  are  related  is  a  form  in 
which  the  essential  feature  of  idealism  may  be  expressed;  the  view 
of  this  purpose  as  good  makes  the  idealism  at  the  same  time  a  moral 
interpretation  of  reality,  and  allows  of  our  classing  each  distinguish- 
able event  as  good  or  evil  according  as  it  tends  to  the  furtherance  or 
hindrance  of  that  purpose. 

This  doctrine  of  the  significance  and  application  of  the  ethical 
concept  would  enable  us  to  reach  a  definite  view  of  the  nature  of 
ethics  and  of  the  way  in  which  it  is  related  to  the  sciences  and  to 
metaphysics.  The  ethical  concept  is  based  upon  the  primary  facts 
of  the  moral  consciousness,  just  as  scientific  concepts  have  as  their 
basis  the  facts  of  direct  experience.  The  primary  facts  of  the  moral 
consciousness  are  themselves  of  the  nature  of  judgment  —  they  are 
approbations  or  disapprobations.  But  all  facts  of  experience  involve 
judgments,  though  these  judgments  may  be  only  of  the  form  "it  is 
here"  or  "it  is  of  this  or  that  nature."  Again,  the  primary  ethical 
facts  or  judgments  cannot  be  assumed  to  be  of  unquestionable  val- 
idity: we  may  approve  what  "is  not  worthy  of  approval,  or  disaj>- 
prove  what  ought  to  have  been  approved.  Our  moral  judgments 
claim  validity;  and  their  claim  is  of  the  nature  of  an  assertion,  not 
that  one  simply  feels  in  such  and  such  a  way,  but  that  something 
ought  or  ought  not  to  be.  They  imply  an  objective  standard.  But 
the  objective  standard,  when  more  clearly  understood,  may  modify 
or  even  reverse  them.  Our  primary  ethical  judgments  —  all  our 
ethical  judgments,  indeed  —  stand  in  need  of  revision  and  criti- 
cism; and  they  receive  this  revision  and  criticism  in  the  course  of 
the  elaboration  of  the  ethical  concept  and  of  its  application  to  the 
worlds  of  fact  and  possibility.  In  the  same  way  it  may  be  contended 
that  the  direct  judgments  of  experience  upon  which  science  is  based 


402  ETHICS 

need  criticism  and  correction;  though  their  variation  may  be  less  in 
amount  than  the  variation  of  moral  judgments.  The  color-blind 
man  identifies  red  with  green,  and  his  judgment  on  this  point  has  to 
be  reversed;  the  hypersensitive  subject  often  confuses  images  with 
percepts;  exact  observation  needs  a  highly  trained  capacity.  The 
correction  and  criticism  which  is  needed  come  from  objective  stand- 
ards; and  these  are  the  result  of  the  comparison  of  many  experiences 
and  the  work  of  many  minds. 

It  is  no  otherwise  in  the  case  of  ethics.  Criticism  brings  to  light 
inconsistencies  in  the  primary  judgments  of  approbation  and  disap- 
probation as  well  as  in  the  later  developments  of  the  moral  judgment. 
And  these  inconsistencies  must  be  dealt  with  in  a  way  similar  to  that 
in  which  we  deal  with  inconsistencies  in  the  judgments  of  perception 
and  of  science.  The  objective  standard  is  not  itself  given  once  for 
all;  it  has  to  be  formed  by  accumulation  and  comparison  of  moral 
experiences.  Like  the  experiences  on  which  science  is  based,  these 
have  to  be  made  as  far  as  possible  harmonious,  and  analysis  has  to 
be  employed  to  bring  out  the  element  of  identity  which  often  lurks 
behind  apparent  contradiction.  They  have  also  to  be  made  as  com- 
prehensive as  possible,  so  that  they  may  be  capable  of  application  to 
all  relevant  facts,  and  that  the  scattered  details  of  the  moral  con- 
sciousness may  be  welded  into  an  harmonious  system.  In  these 
general  respects  the  criticism  of  ethical  concepts  proceeds  upon  the 
same  lines  as  the  criticism  of  scientific  concepts.  The  difference  lies 
in  the  concepts  themselves,  for  ethics  involves  a  point  of  view  to 
which  science  must  always  remain  a  stranger. 


BIBLIOGRAPHICAL   NOTE 

The  relations  of  ethics  are  discussed  in  ahnost  every  ethical  treatise;  special 
reference  may  be  made  to  the  writers  who  have  worked  out  the  theory  of  worth 
or  value,  especially  von  Ehrenfels,  System  der  Wert-theorie  (1897) ;  Meinong,  Psy- 
chologisch-Ethische  Untersuchungen  zur  Werth-theorie  (1894),  and  an  article  in 
Archiv  fiXr  Syst.  Phil.  1895;  Krueger,  Begriff  der  Absolut  Wertvollen  (18p8);  also 
to  articles  by  Standinger  and  by  Natorp  in  Archiv  fur  Syst.  Phil.  (1896);  by 
Wentscher,  Archiv  fur  Syst.  Phil.  1899;  by  Westermarck,  Mind,  1900;  and  by 
Belot,  Revue  de  M&ta'physiqae  et  de  Morale,  1905.  — W.  R.  S. 


PROBLEMS   OF   ETHICS 

BY    PAUL   HENSEL 
(Translated  from  the  German  by  Professor  J.  H.  Woods,  Harvard  University) 

[Paul  Hensel,  Professor  of  Systematic  Philosophy,  University  of  Erlangen, 
since  1902.  b.  May  17,  1860,  Great  Barten,  East  Prussia.  Ph.D.  Freiburg, 
Baden,  1885.  Privat-docent,  Strassburg,  1888-95;  Special  Professor,  Strass- 
burg,  1895-98.  Author  of  The  Ethical  Basis  and  Ethical  Transactions;  Car- 
lyle;  The  Principal  Problems  of  Ethics.] 

Since  the  appearance  of  the  three  chief  works  of  Kant  a  certain 
rhythm  in  the  treatment  of  philosophical  problems,  first  of  all  in 
Germany,  but  also,  in  less  degree,  in  other  civilized  countries,  is  un- 
mistakable. After  an  intense  occupation  with  theoretical  problems 
a  flood  of  ethical  discussion  usually  follows ;  and  this  then  is  usually 
resolved  into  a  renewed  revision  of  sesthetical  problems.  If  I  am 
not  deceived,  we  are  now  at  the  period  of  transition  from  the  second 
to  the  third  epoch;  so  much  the  more  favorable  is  the  time  to  re- 
view the  present  condition  of  ethical  problems.  In  the  first  place, 
then,  it  seems  rather  remarkable  that  recent  ethical  discussion,  so 
intensely  carried  on,  has  resulted  in  a  definite  victory  for  neither  one 
school  nor  the  other.  One  thing  alone,  however,  may  with  some 
accuracy  be  said,  that  the  school  of  utilitarianism  of  the  older  inter- 
pretation by  Bentham,  which  earlier  prevailed  almost  alone  in 
England  with  a  fairly  strong  representation  in  France  and  Germany, 
seems  to  be  withdrawn  from  the  field.  Not  as  if  there  were  no  men 
to-day  who  in  other  times  would  have  sworn  by  Bentham's  flag, 
rather  we  are  here  facing  a  fact  that  a  theory  which  formerly  ap- 
peared in  independence,  now  may  be  deemed  a  special  case  of  a 
more  inclusive  theory,  which  with  the  help  of  its  wider  horizon  can 
remove  a  w^hole  series  of  difficulties,  which  apparently  raised  insolv- 
able  problems  for  the  special  theory.  Utilitarianism,  since  it  had 
started  with  the  examination  of  the  individual,  could  not,  even  in  the 
master-hand  of  Bentham,  transfer  itself  without  remainder  into  the 
greatest  happiness  of  the  greatest  number;  the  interest  paid  on 
the  sacrifice  offered  to  fellow  men,  again  and  again  seemed  dubitable 
and  probable;  again  and  again  the  best  calculation  seemed  to  con- 
sist in  egoism  pure  and  simple.  The  impossibility  of  an  exact  calcula- 
tion of  consequences  in  pleasure  and  in  pain  was  likewise  repeatedly 
emphasized  by  opponents;  the  suggestion  that  we  do  not  count  the 
shrewd  calculator  so  good  as  the  man  who  acts  impulsively  was  also 
not  lacking:  all  these  were  difficulties,  which,  on  the  ground  of  the 
older  utilitarianism,  could  be  evaded  but  not  quite  entirely  put  out 
of  the  world. 


404  ETHICS 

It  is  then  easily  understood  that  the  further  combinations  into 
which  evolution  was  able  to  advance  ethical  questions  have  resulted 
in  the  cessation  of  utilitarianism  as  an  independent  system.  Around 
the  huge  system  of  thought  of  Herbert  Spencer  one  of  the  great  camps 
of  ethical  workers  is  collected.  It  is  not  correct  to  count  Herbert 
Spencer  as  systematizer  of  Darwin's  thoughts;  his  main  thoughts 
were  finished,  before  a  line  of  Darwin  had  appeared.  But  it  is  correct 
that  the  wonderful  inductions  of  Darwin  were  precisely  that  which 
Spencer's  system  needed  in  order  to  begin  its  triumphal  march 
through  the  civilized  world.  Here  the  case  is  the  reverse  of  that  of 
Copernicus  and  Giordano  Bruno:  the  systematizer  precedes  the 
man  of  special  research.  It  is  superfluous  on  American  soil  to  give 
a  description  of  Spencer's  thoughts;  they  have  become  parts  of  the 
general  consciousness.  So  it  may  suffice  to  emphasize  a  few  character- 
istic features,  to  which  my  remarks  shall  be  attached,  since,  other- 
wise, in  view  of  the  richness  of  the  system,  there  might  easily  be 
other  sides  of  it  in  the  mind  of  my  hearers  than  those  to  which  I 
have  here  to  attach  importance. 

The-  characteristic  feature  of  the  system  of  Spencer  is  its  unity  and 
compactness.  Just  as  every  picture  has  a  definite  point  from  which 
it  should  be  seen,  so  also  the  system  of  Spencer  is  a  view  of  the  world 
from  a  quite  definite  point  of  view,  —  that  of  evolution.  Systems 
of  evolution  had  already  occurred  in  philosophy,  —  I  mention  the 
vast  performance  of  Hegel  only,  —  but  that  which  gives  Spencer's 
system  its  characteristic  significance  is  that  here  evolution  is  con- 
ceived not  as  logical,  but  as  biological;  while  in  the  case  of  Hegel 
nature  is  the  vestibule  of  the  realm  of  purpose,  and  therein  alone 
has  its  significance,  Spencer  takes  nature  as  his  point  of  departure, 
and  the  realm  of  human  activity  represents  itself  to  him  merely  as 
the  finest  conformation  of  natural  events.  Here  the  whole  evolution 
from  the  nebula  in  world-space  to  the  most  delicate  relations  between 
man  and  man  are  comprehended  in  one  grand  conception.  The  same 
amount  of  force  which  then  existed  in  world-space  exists  still  to-day, 
only  in  infinitely  more  differentiated  form.  The  new  which  is  pro- 
duced is  nothing  else  than  the  transformed  old,  but  transformed  in 
an  essential  relation,  in  the  direction  towards  constantly  increasing 
complexity  of  relations  in  which  single  things  and  centres  of  force 
stand  to  each  other. 

If  it  be  asked  what  this  principle  is  which  is  the  ground  for  this 
differentiation,  a  glance  at  the  behavior  of  organisms  informs  us.  In 
them  we  can  most  clearly  recognize  effects  which  result,  with  the 
necessity  of  laws  of  nature,  from  increasing  differentiation.  The 
undifferentiated  individual  is  powerless  in  the  presence  of  every 
change  of  his  environment.  Banished  to  its  accidental  place,  the 
plant  must  wait  for  what  happens  to  it.    Only  within  a  narrow  limit 


PROBLEMS   OF   ETHICS  405 

can  it  maintain  its  existence.  Better  equipped  we  find  the  animal, 
especially  when  it  has  gathered  into  social  groups,  either  for  pro- 
tection against  carnivora  or  for  the  breeding  of  progeny  in  common. 
The  young  steer  has  an  infinitely  better  prospect  to  maintain  itself, 
to  grow  up,  than  the  single  egg  in  the  spawn  of  the  sturgeon. 

So  it  is,  before  all  else,  the  fact  of  social  combination  which  attracts 
to  itself  the  attention  of  the  revolutionary  ethicist.  His  ethics  is 
social  ethics.  The  analysis  of  the  historical  development  of  mankind 
forms  the  standard,  in  which  the  social  combinations  have  resulted, 
and  in  which  greater  and  world-inclusive  formations  have  replaced 
those  earlier,  smaller,  and  smallest,  usually  engaged  in  war  with 
each  other.  It  is  a  long  way  from  the  time  when  hospes  was  equivalent 
to  hostis  to  international  expositions,  and  the  single  stages  of  this 
way  reflect  themselves  in  the  moral  behavior  of  the  individuals. 
The  old  question,  which  in  so  many  ways  agitated  the  English 
ethics  of  the  seventeenth  and  eighteenth  centuries,  the  question, 
whether  man  should  be  regarded  as  an  originally  egoistic  being,  or 
whether  equally  original,  benevolent  instincts  must  be  ascribed  to 
him,  is  transferred  by  evolutionists  of  to-day  beyond  the  realm  of 
man  to  that  of  his  animal  ancestors  and,  in  this  case,  in  favor  of  the 
originality  of  egoism.  But  long  before  man  appeared  as  an  inde- 
pendent species  the  effects  of  the  life  of  the  horde  must  have  shown 
themselves  in  him,  since  those  communities  only  in  which  the  single 
members  were  bound  to  each  other  by  sympathy  had  any  prospect 
of  survival.  It  is  therefore  possible  to  speak  of  animal  ethics.  The 
interesting  attempts  which  Darwin  had  made  in  this  field  were  taken 
by  Spencer,  as  a  whole,  into  his  system.  It  must,  however,  be  con- 
ceded that  we  must  observe  the  full  development  of  this  process, 
first  of  all,  in  man,  and  the  tendency  then  consists  in  a  constant 
decrease  of  egoistic,  as  compared  with  altruistic,  actions.  How  it 
was  possible  that  the  individual  was  ever  willing  to  renounce  the 
amounts  of  pleasure,  which  he  could  obtain,  in  favor  of  others, 
Spencer  skillfully  tried  to  explain  by  the  introduction  of  the  egoistic- 
altruistic  feelings.  These  give  the  impulse  to  actions  which  are  useful 
to  the  community,  but  which  give  to  the  doer  honor  and  distinction, 
and  thus,  from  egoistic  motives,  make  actions  which  promote  the 
welfare  of  the  community  commendable.  But  those  actions  which 
damage  the  community  are  visited  with  punishment  of  all  kinds. 
The  theory  of  sanctions  in  Bentham  and  Mill  here  passes  over  into 
the  more  extensive  system  of  evolution.  For  modern  theory  of 
evolution,  by  the  broader  biological  foundation  of  its  system,  suc- 
ceeds in  explaining  why  even,  in  the  case  of  those  who  cannot  over- 
look the  consequences  of  such  actions  as  are  injurious  to  their  own 
person,  these  consequences  are  still  ignored.  The  fact  of  the  con- 
science, for  the  consistent  Benthamite  a  negligible  quantity,  forms 


406  ETHICS 

the  keystone  of  Spencer's  ethics,  and  affords  the  chance  of  making 
the  theory  of  heredity  applicable  in  a  new  field  of  ethical  speculation. 
It  is,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  impossible  for  the  single  individual  to 
calculate,  by  Bentham's  receipt,  all  the  consequences  of  pleasure  or 
of  pain  which  result  from  the  actions  for  his  own  welfare.  The 
individual  need  not,  however,  undertake  this  calculation  at  all.  He 
does  not  begin  at  the  beginning  of  making  his  experiences  in  this 
world;  he  enjoys  the  heaped-up  treasure  of  experiences  which,  before 
him,  long-forgotten  generations  of  ancestors  had  made;  and  the 
sum  of  these  experiences  he  calls  his  conscience.  This  voice  of  the 
conscience  restrains  the  individual  from  anti-social  actions,  which, 
in  accordance  with  experience,  must  lead  to  an  injury  to  his  own 
person;  in  accordance,  of  course,  with  the  experience  not  of  single 
ancestors  but  of  the  whole  line.  Here,  again,  a  selective  process  in  the 
struggle  for  existence  is  being  completed.  Men  with  no  conscience  at 
all  or  with  an  only  imperfectly  developed  conscience  have  to  contend 
with  disadvantages  similar  to  those  in  whom  the  corporal  adjustment 
to  the  modern  conditions  of  civilization  have  proved  defective;  they 
are  exterminated  by  seclusion  in  prison  or  by  execution,  as  the  others 
by  diseases  which  their  bodies  cannot  resist.  The  criminal  of  to-day 
might  perhaps  have  been,  in  primitive  times,  a  respected  member  of 
his  horde,  perhaps,  even  a  great  chief.  To-day  he  can  be  regarded 
only  as  an  atavistic  survivor,  who  fits  into  our  conditions  as  little 
as  a  living  ichthyosaurus  into  this  lecture-hall.  Again,  it  is  to  be 
hoped,  it  is  even  definitely  to  be  predicted,  that  many  who  to-day 
are  quite  irreproachable  in  moral  respects,  in  later  times  will  no 
longer  succeed  in  satisfying  the  requirements  in  the  form  of  their 
grandson  or  great-grandson.  For  the  progress  is  a  biological  necessity; 
and  he  who  cannot  attach  himself  to  its  ways  is  submerged. 

It  is  small  disparagement  for  this  vast  construction  of  the  connec- 
tion between  the  moral  life  of  the  individual  and  the  total  evolution 
of  the  associations  of  men,  of  organisms,  of  the  whole,  that,  now  espe- 
cially in  English  ethics,  a  bitter  strife  has  broken  forth,  which  we  may 
regard  as  the  one-sided  elaboration  of  the  individualistic  parts  of 
Spencer's  ethics  on  the  one  side,  of  the  social  on  the  other  side. 
While  the  orthodox  disciples  of  Spencer  insist  that  such  progress 
only  can  be  kept  iv.  aim  which  must  assure  to  the  individual,  to  the 
fit  the  most  unrestricted  possible  amount  of  free  movement,  while 
the  whole  rigor  of  the  process  of  selection  must  fall  upon  the  unad- 
justed and  the  unfit,  the  socialist  tendencies  of  our  time  tend  to 
advocate  a  reversal  of  this  harsh  result  and  to  advocate  both  the 
united  struggle  of  human  society,  by  suppressing  over-energetic 
individuals,  and  the  preservation  of  the  economically  weak.  Though 
it  would  be  interesting  to  trace  this  division  "to  its  final  grounds,  I 
must  limit  myself  to  note  the  fact  that  the  socialist  movement 


PROBLEMS   OF   ETHICS  407 

seems  here  also  to  be  in  advance,  —  at  least,  so  far  as  European 
movements  of  thought  are  concerned;  and  that  they  are  in  the 
condition  to  compensate  for  their  departure  from  the  teachings  of 
the  master  by  an  appeal  to  the  main  thoughts  of  his  system,  con- 
cerns me  just  here.  Doubtless  socialistic  thought  is  on  the  whole 
in  advance  when  compared  with  liberal  and  individualistic  thought. 
And,  under  these  circumstances,  the  inference  for  every  disciple  of 
Darwin's  theory  of  evolution  is  simple;  that  here  again  is  a  case 
of  survival  of  the  fittest;  that  socialistic  ideals  represent  a  higher 
form  of  adjustment;  that  just  by  the  fact  of  their  victory  the  ne- 
cessity and  justification  of  this  victory  is  placed  beyond  doubt.  It 
helped  little  that  the  venerable  thinker  himself  in  the  last  years  of 
his  rich  and  active  life  descended  into  the  arena  of  the  contest  and 
warned  his  beloved  England  against  the  dangers  of  this  socialistic 
tendency.  It  was  inconsistent  that  he  tried  to  brand  these  thoughts 
as  a  retrograde  movement,  as  a  step  backward,  since  his  own  system 
with  its  powerful  optimism  affords  no  possibility  for  victorious 
retrograde  movements.  Even  imperfection  and  evil  has  for  Spencer 
only  the  significance  of  an  imperfect  progress;  and  the  thought 
that  imperfection  could  even  win  the  victory  over  the  perfect,  that 
must  be  warned  against  it,  could  only  be  nonsense  in  connection 
with  his  system.  For  him,  as  for  Hegel,  the  final  formula,  obtained 
it  is  true  by  a  very  different  way,  is  the  thesis:  The  actual  is 
rational. 

But  just  this  reference  to  Hegel's  system  makes  clear  to  us  the 
opposition  which  Herbert  Spencer's  system  found  in  Germany, 
first  of  all,  but  also  in  -wide  circles  in  England  and  in  America.  If 
it  could  be  objected  against  Hegel  that  the  activity  of  the  individual, 
in  contrast  to  the  might  of  the  developing  process  of  the  logical  idea, 
is  reduced  to  insignificance,  this  consideration  returns  with  doubled 
force  in  contrast  to  the  concept  of  the  thought  of  development,  which 
is  found  in  the  modern  theory  of  evolution  of  Spencer.  For  here 
it  is  not  teleological  necessities  which  prevail,  but  causal.  To  have 
proved  evolution  by  the  laws  of  nature  is  precisely  his  system's  title 
to  fame.  The  question  must  then  be  raised  whether  an  obligation 
to  any  definite  practical  action  can  be  deduced  from  the  proof  of  the 
necessity  of  any  event.  If  the  development  is  necessary,  it  will  be 
completed  whether  I  cooperate  with  it  or  not.  If  it  needs  my  coopera- 
tion, it  need  not  be  regarded  as  a  law  of  nature.  It  is  exactly  the 
same  difficulty  which  beset  the  Stoics,  when  they  tried  to  harmon- 
ize the  determinism  of  world  events  with  the  demands  which  their 
ethics  put  upon  the  moral  resolves  of  the  individual.  It  is  absurd 
to  will  any  necessary  event  of  the  laws  of  nature;  I  can  suspend  my 
action  so  that  I  count  upon  the  occurrence  of  such  an  incident,  but 
I  cannot  make  this  incident  the  object  of  my  will.   I  can  decide  that 


408  ETHICS 

I  will  observe  an  eclipse  of  the  moon,  but  I  cannot  will  the  occurrence 

of  this  eclipse  of  the  moon,  or  not  will  it. 

If  we  reduce  the  difficulty  to  the  simplest  formula,  it  would  be  as 
follows:  the  theory  of  evolution  did  not  distinguish  between  two 
completely  different  kinds  of  attitudes  on  the  part  of  human  mental 
activity;  between  the  knowledge  of  the  necessity  of  what  exists  and 
its  judgment  by  standards  of  value.  But  it  is  precisely  with  the 
latter  that  ethics  has  to  do.  It  is,  like  logic  and  aesthetics,  a  science 
of  values;  the  interest  in  the  question  how  something  has  come  to  be, 
is  quite  different  from  the  interest  in  determining  its  value.  Every- 
thing has  come  to  be,  the  valueless  as  well  as  the  valued,  with  the 
same  necessity;  that  is  a  self-evident  presupposition  of  all  explana- 
tory science.  The  bungling  drawing  of  a  school-boy  and  the  Sistine 
Madonna,  the  hallucinations  of  a  lunatic  and  the  thought  of  a 
Herbert  Spencer,  a  demonic  crime  and  a  deed  of  the  purest  ethical 
fulfillment  of  duty,  are,  in  the  same  sense,  necessary;  but  with  the 
knowledge  of  this  necessity  we  have  not  come  a  single  step  nearer 
to  the  task  of  their  valuation. 

The  difference  between  these  two  kinds  of  attitudes  has  perhaps 
never  been  more  clearly  sketched  than  in  Fichte's  book  On  the 
Calling  of  Alan.  If  we  assume  that  I  have  a  fully  adequate  scientific 
knowledge  of  the  course  of  nature,  I  might  discern  that  this  grain 
of  sand  which  the  storm  has  set  in  motion  could  not  drift  a  hair's 
breadth  farther,  unless  the  whole  previous  course  of  nature  had  been 
quite  different;  what  then  would  be  gained  for  my  own  moral  action? 
The  answer  must  be:  Nothing.  More  than  that,  if  this  point  of  view 
were  the  only  possible  for  man,  then  this  action  would  have  no 
longer,  as  a  moral  action,  any  significance,  and  could  have  none; 
since  as  a  part  of  the  world  event  alike  in  value  to  all  other  parts  it 
would  remain  like  in  value,  and  it  would  be  meaningless  to  select  and 
emphasize  out  of  this  continuum  of  facts  and  environments,  alike  in 
value,  single  elements  as  especially  valuable  and  significant.  The 
man  who  could  not  resign  himself  to  this  knowledge,  who  could 
not  be  satisfied  to  continue,  in  cool  content,  at  the  point  of  view  of 
the  silent  contemplation  of  causes,  must  fall  into  conflicts  similar 
to  those  which  Carlyle  so  vividly  described  in  Sartor  Resartus.  We 
must  then,  in  order  to  an  understanding  for  this  new  problem, 
provisionally  disregard,  above  all  else,  whatever  the  theory  of  evo- 
lution has  accomplished  by  way  of  scientific  explanation,  and  reserve 
for  a  later  investigation  the  ethical  valuation  of  this  sequence  of 
development.  The  question  which  is  now  to  occupy  us  is  directed, 
first  of  all,  to  the  subject  of  our  moral  valuation.  What  do  we  call 
good  or  bad? 

This  is  the  main  question  of  all  normative  ethics  in  general,  and  its 
answer  by  Kant  will  always  remain  a  brilliant  feat  in  this  field.    He 


PROBLEMS   OF   ETHICS  409 

proved,  in  the  first  place,  that  this  predicate  can  be  properly  applied 
to  no  action  whatever,  that  we  can  speak  of  a  good  action  in  figur- 
ative language  only,  when  we  believe  that  we  can  make  from  this 
action  an  inference  with  regard  to  something  else,  —  the  disposition 
of  the  actor;  and  that  the  same  action  which  we  do  not  hesitate 
to  describe  as  good,  on  the  supposition  of  the  correctness  of  this 
inference,  loses  directly  this  character  as  soon  as  doubt  of  the  cor- 
rectness of  the  inference  arises.  This  disposition,  which  we  distin- 
guish in  this  way,  which  forms  the  substrate  of  our  moral  valuation, 
we  call  the  good  will,  and  the  Magna  Charta  of  the  Kantian  ethics 
consists  in  the  celebrated  thesis:  Nothing  can  possibly  be  good 
except  a  good  will.  This  reasoning  appears  to  be  as  self-evident 
as  its  result  is  important. 

The  whole  ethical  process  is  removed  within  the  soul.  While  the 
theory  of  evolution  and,  still  more,  utilitarianism  could  still  hope 
to  obtain,  with  the  character  of  the  work,  at  the  same  time  an  ex- 
pression with  regard  to  the  ethical  value  of  the  action;  while,  in  this 
combination  of  ideas,  the  ethical  goodness  of  the  disposition  could 
be  judged  by  the  usefulness  or  value  to  civilization  of  the  performance 
done,  so  that  both  these  systems  would  have  essentially  the  character 
of  an  ethics  of  results,  we  have  in  Kant  and  his  successors,  most 
decidedly,  an  ethics  of  dispositions.  It  has  rightly  been  pointed 
out  that  this  ethics  could  grow  only  upon  Protestant  soil,  that  here 
the  same  contradiction  prevails  which  Luther  once  summed  up  in  the 
words:  "Good  works  do  not  make  the  good  man,  but  the  good  man 
creates  good  works."  All  the  excellences,  but  all  the  weaknesses 
also,  of  Protestantism,  cling  to  Kant's  ethics. 

First,  let  us  follow  the  further  stages  of  Kant's  thought.  How 
must  a  good  will  be  constituted,  so  that  we  may  count  it  as  ethically 
good?  All  our  acts  happen  in  order  to  fulfill  a  purpose.  The  character 
of  the  action  depends  upon  the  character  of  the  purpose,  which  the 
actor  proposes  for  himself,  which  he  affirms  with  his  will,  which  he 
makes  his  own.  But  if  the  purpose  be  no  longer  willed,  then  all  the 
actions  cease,  which  hitherto  had  had  to  be  accomplished  for  its 
fulfillment.  All  those  purposes,  which  under  the  circumstances 
cannot  be  willed,  cannot  therefore  produce  that  lasting  constitution 
of  the  will  which  we  understand  under  the  term  the  good  will.  But 
among  the  different  motivations  of  the  will,  there  are  some  which 
for  the  observer  become  separated.  They  have  not  a  character  such 
that  they  could,  under  any  circumstances,  cease 'to  motivate  the 
will;  they  are  necessary  and  universal  determinations  of  the  will. 
The  imperative  which  they  contain  and  with  which  they  demand 
action  has  not  the  hypothetical  form:  "If  thou  wilt  obtain  this  or 
that,  you  must; "  but  the  absolute:  " Thou  shalt."  It  is  a  categorical 
imperative,  to  which  the  will  is  here  subordinated,  which  determines 


410  ETHICS 

my  actions;  and  such  a  categorical  imperative  we  term  duty.  Only 
the  dutiful  will  is  good.  It  is  clear  that  this  determination  shows 
an  exact  analogy  to  the  other  norms  of  judgment  in  the  logical  and 
the  sesthetical  field.  The  principle  of  contradiction  states  nothing 
at  all  with  regard  to  the  single  thoughts,  it  only  asserts  that  our  think- 
ing can  then  alone  make  a  claim  upon  a  logical  valuation  while  it 
fills  the  condition  which  the  principle  of  contradiction  states.  Like- 
wise, the  impulses  of  our  wills  can  be  morally  valued  only  when  they 
refer  to  an  absolute  "Thou  shalt;"  if  this  is  not  the  case,  they  are 
excluded  from  the  range  of  valuation,  just  as  the  play  of  our  fancy, 
which  does  not  recognize  the  principle  of  contradiction,  is  excluded 
from  the  realm  of  the  norm  of  scientific  thinking. 

Here  again  the  normal  action  of  ethics  is  represented  as  a  selective 
process.  While  the  evolutionist  ethicist  can  estimate  every  single 
content  of  human  consciousness  with  reference  to  the  point  whether 
it  is  preservative  of  the  species  or  not,  and  thus  give  it  ethical  value, 
the  realm  of  the  Kantian  ethics  is  much  more  confined.  Only  those 
impulses  of  the  will  occur  with  conscious  subordination  under  the 
command  of  duty,  or  in  conscious  opposition  to  it  fall  within  the 
realm  of  moral  valuation.  All  others  —  and  their  name  is  legion  — 
must  be  termed  unmoral.  Not  as  if  they  become  thereby  actually 
valueless;  they  may  stand  as  high  as  you  please  in  the  intellectual, 
aesthetic,  or  religious  scale  of  values.  But  to  bring  them  under  just 
the  moral  norms  of  judgment  would  be  an  attempt  at  an  unappli- 
able  object.  This  is  the  point,  perhaps,  where  the  Kantian  ethics 
gives  the  hardest  shock  to  the  healthy  human  understanding.  It 
will  always  seem  a  paradox  that  we  have  a  moral  act  when  a  man 
with  strong  desires  for  theft,  after  a  severe  inner  struggle,  does  not 
put  a  silver  spoon  into  his  pocket,  while  the  man  who  omits  all  this 
quite  as  a  matter  of  course  may  have  no  claim  upon  moral  desert. 
And  yet  each  one  of  us  would  feel  it  as  an  insult,  if  he  should  be 
praised  for  such  omission.  The  solution  of  this  difficulty  lies  in  the 
distinction  of  the  value  of  the  single  resolve  and  that  of  the  whole 
moral  personality.  The  man  who  is  still  led  into  temptation  by  silver 
spoons  stands  morally  upon  the  same  plane  upon  which  the  scholar 
stands  who  struggles  with  extreme  mental  effort  to  calculate  a  simple 
example  in  multiplication.  In  the  case  of  the  more  advanced  person 
our  moral  approval  is  not  aroused  because  he  no  longer  needs,  in 
this  simple  case,  to  appeal  to  the  law  of  duty,  but  because  we  be- 
lieve that  we  may  conclude  that  his  moral  personality  is  attacking 
other  more  difficult  problems  with  full  force,  and  that  he  is  here  in 
himself  feeling  the  full  weight  of  the  contest.  If  we  were  deceived 
in  this,  if  it  prove  true  that  he,  content  with  what  had  been  attained, 
had  withdrawn  to  the  position  of  the  ethical  capitalist,  our  ethical 
interest  in  him  would  likewise  cease,  just  as  our  intellectual  interest 


PROBLEMS   OF   ETHICS  411 

ceases  in  the  scholar  for  whom  there  are  no  more  problems  in  his 
science.  From  this  point  of  view  the  result  is  necessary  that  the 
category  of  duties,  to  speak  with  Hegel,  is  absolutely  infinite;  and 
in  this  perhaps  lies  the  considerable  difference  between  modern  and 
ancient  ethics.  For  ancient  ethics  the  ideal  of  the  wise  man  was 
a  distinctly  finitely  determined  amount.  However  difficult  it  might 
be  to  fulfill  the  conditions  for  it,  it  could  still  be  fulfilled  in  a  human 
life;  and  a  further  advance  beyond  this  fulfilled  ideal  would  have 
been  to  the  Greeks  an  absurdity:  it  is  the  "nothing  too  much" 
transferred  to  the  ethical  point  of  view.  It  is  otherwise  in  modern 
ethics,  and  with  this  is  connected  the  change  in  that  the  concept  of 
the  infinite  has  become  a  concept  of  value.  It  is  as  Carlyle  says: 
"  Fulfill  the  next  duty  which  presents  itself  to  thee,  and  when  thou 
hast  fulfilled  it,  wait  for  ten,  twenty,  a  hundred  to  be  fulfilled."  But 
we  recognize  the  degree  of  ethical  development  which  a  man  has 
attained  by  noting  that  it  is  no  longer  duty  to  him. 

If  the  limits  of  the  moral  valuation  have  been  much  restricted 
by  the  introduction  of  the  concept  of  unmoral  actions,  it  has  been 
extended  in  the  other  direction  by  the  insight  that  now  every  action 
which  happens  in  fulfillment  of  a  command  of  duty  is  to  be  valued 
as  the  result  of  a  moral  disposition.  We  come  thus  to  the  problem 
which,  since  the  time  of  the  ancient  sophists,  has  not  ceased  to  occupy 
minds,  and  which  may  most  simply  be  termed  the  anthropological 
problem.  What  in  the  world  is  there  that  is  not  by  individuals  and 
by  people  deemed  to  be  moral!  With  what  strange  contents  the 
formal  "  Thou  shalt "  of  morality  is  filled !  In  face  of  these  contradic- 
tions, is  there  any  sense  at  all  in  speaking  of  ethical  commands?  All 
skeptical  attacks  upon  ethics  find  in  such  considerations  their  strong- 
est support;  and  here  again  the  answer  is  easy  when  we  reflect  upon 
the  analogy  with  science,  art,  and  religion.  Aristotle  and  Democritus, 
Hegel  and  Hobbes,have  taught  very  differently,  and  yet  all  have  been 
busy  with  science.  Raphael  and  Menzel  are  surely  to  be  valued  as 
artists;  Mahomet  and  Buddha  were  both  religious  geniuses  of  the  first 
magnitude.  Why  should  it  be  different  in  the  field  of  ethics?  What 
other  men  have  held  to  be  moral,  how  they  have  acted,  this  can  be 
valuable  to  me,  in  order  for  me  to  become  clear  with  regard  to  my 
own  moral  determination,  just  as  the  artist  sees  the  works  of  other 
masters,  just  as  the  scientific  man  must  know  the  theorems  of  others. 
But  all  this  cannot  be  the  standard  for  the  formation  of  my  own  life. 
I  am,  once  for  all,  placed  in  this  world,  to  be  active  there;  I  am 
responsible  to  myself  .for  what  I  wish  to  accomplish  with  this  life. 
And  so  it  can,  it  is  true,  be  an  encouragement  to  me  that  other  men 
have  felt  in  themselves  the  same  motive  to  moral  activity;  I  can 
give  them  my  hand  as  striving  for  the  same  with  me  through  the 
separating  centuries  and  across  the  estranging  seas.    But  their  way 


412  ETHICS 

of  solving  the  great  problems  of  life  cannot  be  the  standard  for  me 
save  in  the  sense  that  I  receive  them  into  my  will,  recognize  them  as 
valid  for  my  own  life. 

So,  then,  the  whole  weight  of  the  distinction,  the  whole  moral 
process,  is  transferred  to  the  individual.  He  is  the  point  of  depart- 
ure and  the  goal  of  the  struggle  for  a  content  in  life.  Is  this  now 
egoism?  This  much-discussed  question  also  suffers,  as  I  believe,  by 
a  defect  in  the  statement  of  the  problem.  If  it  is  intended  that  that 
action  is  meant  by  egoism,  the  motive  for  which  is  one's  own  welfare 
or  happiness,  by  altruism,  however,  the  action  which  aims  at  the 
happiness  of  others,  it  is  quite  clear  that  these  two  contrasts  have  as 
little  meaning  for  the  ethics  of  disposition  as  the  complementary 
contrast  of  beautiful  and  ugly.  Moral  action  is  completely  indifferent 
with  regard  to  these  contrasts.  Moral  actions  can  be  characterized 
as  altruistic  as  well  as  egoistic,  and  the  same  is  the  case  for  unmoral 
or  bad  actions.  By  knowing  that  distinct  advantages  have  resulted 
to  the  doer  from  an  action,  or  that  "the  greatest  happiness  of  the 
greatest  number"  has  resulted  from  it,  I  have  not  gained  one  step 
for  the  moral  valuation  of  this  action.  I  should  surely  act  immorally 
if  I  omitted  an  action  acknowledged  as  moral  by  me  because  it 
would  involve  pain  for  others  and  thus  would  have  an  anti-altruistic 
character.  Whence  this  confusion  of  the  altruistic  with  the  moral 
arose  is  easy  to  see.  Long  before  the  child  could  himself  act  morally, 
it  must  be  accustomed  to  feel  that  its  beloved  self  cannot  be  the  sole 
standard  for  its  action;  and  to  the  end  that  it  keep  peace  and  content 
with  its  brothers  and  playmates,  it  is  properly  accustomed  to  regard 
in  its  action  the  welfare  of  the  human  beings  about  it.  That  is  a 
preparatory  step  to  moral  action;  but,  strictly  speaking,  it  can  be 
counted  as  moral  by  those  only  who  are  determined  not  to  recognize 
the  limits  between  psychological  motivation  and  normative  deter- 
mination. 

It  would  be  an  interesting  task  to  trace  the  relations  into  which 
the  autonomous  moral  individual  enters  with  the  great  moral 
institutions  which  dominate  the  community  and  have  combined  in 
usage,  society,  and  state,  and  which  Hegel  described  in  a  happy 
expression  as  "  objective  morality."  Here  it  is  no  longer  the  regard 
for  the  weal  or  woe  of  fellow  men  which  strives  to  gain  influence 
over  my  action;  here  the  ethical  will  of  past  generations  of  my  own 
ancestors  accosts  and  asks  me  whether  I  can  bring  my  action  into 
harmony  with  that  which  they  willed  and  for  which  they  strove. 
It  is  a  slight  disadvantage  to  the  ethically  directed  man  that,  in 
order  to  protect  these  moral  institutions  from  injury,  an  arsenal 
of  punishments,  of  social  influences,  of  boycotts,  and  of  whatever 
finer  or  coarser  means  of  compulsion  there  may  be,  are  set  up.  This 
arsenal  is  necessary  to  sustain  the  social  structure  which  alone 


PROBLEMS   OF   ETHICS  413 

affords  the  chance  for  moral  action;  and  he  who  calculates  with 
pleasure  and  pain,  who  tries  to  arrange  his  life  as  happily  as  possible, 
will  be  restrained  by  shrewd  calculation  from  injuring  the  prevailing 
moral  institutions.  The  moral  man  has  nothing  to  do  with  such 
considerations.  When  he  affirms  the  objective  morality,  he  does  so 
because  he  recognizes  his  moral  will  as  identical  with  that  of  previous 
generations  which  have  made  these  forms.  But  the  time  can  come 
when  he  discovers  that  a  moral  life  within  these  forms  is  no  longer 
possible  for  him,  when  with  deep  regret  he  sees  the  bond  of  continuity 
break  which  knit  him  in  affection  with  the  past,  when  he  must 
resolve  to  enter  new  untrodden  paths,  just  as  Copernicus  was  forced 
to  resolve  to  substitute  a  new  knowledge  for  those  which  had  satisfied 
centuries.  Such  a  man  will  endure  calmly  and  patiently  the  con- 
sequences which  result  from  such  a  course;  he  will  not  expect  to 
be  justified,  through  the  purity  of  his  intentions,  in  the  eyes  of  his 
fellows,  if  he  undertakes  to  lay  hands  on  the  institutions  which  the 
moral  consciousness  of  his  contemporaries  recognizes  as  valid.  But 
he  will  also  know  that  these  same  institutions  owe  what  sacredness 
they  possess  to  the  blood  of  previous  martyrs,  that  these  shadows 
of  a  past  can  only  then  speak  to  a  living  generation  when  they  have 
tasted  the  sacred  blood  of  sacrifice. 

So  then  we  see  two  great  movements  in  our  time  struggling  about 
the  ethical  questions.  The  one  has  on  its  side  the  whole  apparatus 
of  scientific  conceptions,  the  presupposition  of  necessary  events 
without  exceptions,  the  knowledge  that  the  single  individual  is  an 
infinitely  small  element  in  a  necessary  sequence  of  development.  It 
can  explain  everything,  deduce  everything  from  its  conditions.  At 
one  point  only  its  power  breaks  down :  it  cannot  make  the  individual 
comprehend  why  he  should  raise  a  finger  to  keep  in  motion  this 
machine  which  goes  of  itself. 

And,  opposed  to  this,  is  the  other  movement,  which  rests  upon  the 
one  fact  that  the  point  of  view  of  its  opponent,  the  scientific,  is  also 
a  relation  of  reality  to  values,  and  that  man  alone  introduces  these 
values  into  reality,  measures  and  tests  it  by  these  values.  According 
to  this  movement,  every  new  human  life  has  the  question  put  to  it, 
what  it  can  accomplish  with  these  values,  whether  it  is  capable  of 
making  something  out  of  reality,  out  of  itself,  which  has  in  itself  a 
value  such  as  to  raise  it  above  the  flux  of  appearances  as  the  bearer 
of  these  values.  Everything  previous  as  well  as  everything  subsequent 
vanishes  before  these  thoughts  that  it  is  now  day,  that  the  night  is 
soon  coming  when  no  man  can  work^that  at  the  day's  end  the  day's 
work  must  be  done.  But  what  each  recognizes  as  his  day's  work,  he 
must  himself  find  within  himself.   This  decision  is  his  destiny. 

I  cannot  better  close  than  with  the  words  of  the  man  whose  life 
had  little  joy,  but  who  grappled  with  these  questions  in  the  soUtude 


414  ETHICS 

of  Craigenputtock,  in  the  supreme  solitude  of  the  human  wilderness 
of  London,  with  a  seriousness  which  still  to-day  proves  to  be  soul- 
wooing  and  soul- winning :  "  Centuries  have  passed  that  thou  might- 
est  be  born,  and  centuries  are  waiting  in  dumb  expectation  of  what 
thou  wilt  accomplish  with  this  life,  now  that  it  has  begun."  And 
what  this  hfe  can  offer  Carlyle,  by  combining  the  thoughts  of  Fichte 
and  of  Goethe,  has  united  in  the  call: 

"  Work  and  despair  not." 


SECTION  F  — .ESTHETICS 


SECTION  F  — .ESTHETICS 


{Hall  4,  September  23,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairal^n:  Professor  James  H.  Tufts,  University  of  Chicago. 
Speakers:   Dr.  Henry  Rutgers  Marshall,  New  York  City. 
Professor  Max  Dessoir,  University  of  Berlin. 
Secretary:  Professor  Max  Meyer,  University  of  Missouri. 


THE  RELATION   OF   ESTHETICS  TO   PSYCHOLOGY  AND 

PHILOSOPHY 

BY  HENRY  RUTGEES  MARSHALL 

[Henry  Rutgers  Marshall,  Practicing  Architect,  President  of  the  New  York 
Chapter,  American  Institute  of  Architects,  Member  of  Art  Commission, 
Citv  of  New  York.  b.  July  22,  1852,  New  York  City.  B.A.  Columbia  Uni- 
versity, 1873;  U.K.  ibid.  1875;  L.H.D.  Rutgers  College,  1903.  Member 
American  Psychological  Association,  Society  of  American  Naturalists,  Fel- 
low American  Institute  of  Architects,  Honorary  Member  National  Society  of 
Mural  Painters,  Member  American  Philosophical  Association.  Author  of 
Pain,  Pleasure,  and  Esthetics;  ^^sthetic  Principles ;  Instinct  and  Reason.] 

If  conventional  divisions  of  time  are  to  serve  as  means  by  which  we 
may  mark  the  movement  of  thought  as  it  develops,  we  may  well 
say  that  the  nineteenth  century  saw  a  real  awakening  in  relation 
to  aesthetics  among  those  who  concern  themselves  with  accurate 
thinking,  —  a  coming  to  consciousness,  as  it  were,  of  the  importance 
to  the  philosophy  of  life  of  the  existence  of  beauty  in  the  world,  and 
of  the  sense  of  beauty  in  man. 

And  with  this  awakening  came  a  marked  breadth  of  inquiry;  an 
attempt  to  throw  the  light  given  by  psychological  analysis  upon  the 
broad  field  of  aesthetics,  and  an  effort  to  grasp  the  relations  within 
the  realm  in  which  beauty  holds  sway  to  philosophy  as  a  whole. 

That  the  questions  thus  presented  to  us  have  been  answered,  I 
imagine  few,  if  any,  would  claim;  rather  may  we  say  that  the  nine- 
teenth century  set  the  problems  which  it  concerns  the  aesthetician 
of  the  twentieth  century  to  solve;  and  this  without  underestimating 
the  value  of  the  work  of  the  masters  in  aesthetics  who  lived  and 
vsTote  in  the  century  so  lately  closed,  some  of  whom  are  fortunately 
with  us  still. 

Of  these  present  problems  M.  Dessoir  will  treat  in  his  address  to 
follow  mine;  in  the  regretted  absence  of  Professor  Lipps  the  privilege 
has  been  granted  to  me  to  consider  with  you  briefly  the  relations 
of  aesthetics  to  psychology,  and  to  philosophy,  which  must  in  the 


418  ^ESTHETICS 

end  determine  the  nature  of  the  problems  to  be  studied  by  the  aesthe- 
tician,  and  the  import  of  the  solutions  of  these  problems  which  they 
present   for   our   consideration. 

I.  The  Relation  of  Esthetics  to  Psychology 

We  live  in  what  may  well  be  called  the  era  of  psychological  develop- 
ment, an  era  marked  by  the  recognition  of  the  truth  that  no  philo- 
sophical view  of  life  can  be  adequate  which  does  not  take  full  account 
of  the  experience  of  the  individual  human  spirit  which  interprets  this 
life.  And  so  quite  naturally  for  ourselves,  and  in  all  probability 
quite  in  accord  with  the  habit  of  thought  of  the  immediate  future, 
we  begin  our  study  by  the  consideration  of  the  relation  of  aesthetics 
to  psychology. 

In  turning  for  light  to  psychology,  the  sesthetician  finds  himself  of 
course  asking  what  is  the  nature  of  the  states  of  mind  related  to  his 
inquiry;  and  here  at  once  he  finds  himself  confronted  with  a  distinc- 
tion which  must  be  made  if  a  correct  aesthetic  doctrine  is  to  become 
established.  He  notes  that  there  is  a  sharp  difference  between  (1) 
the  mental  attitude  of  an  artist  who  produces  works  of  beauty;  and 
(2)  the  mental  attitude  of  a  man  at  the  moment  when  he  appreciates 
beauty  in  his  experience.^  The  failure  to  note  this  distinction  has  in 
my  view  led  to  much  confusion  of  thought  among  the  sestheticians 
of  the  past,  and  to  the  defense  of  dogmas  which  otherwise  would 
not  have  been  maintained. 

That  this  distinction  is  an  important  one  becomes  clear  in  the 
fact  that  the  sense  of  beauty  is  aroused  in  us  by  objects  in  nature 
which  bear  no  relation  to  what  men  call  fine  art.  The  mental  state 
of  the  appreciator  of  beauty  has  therefore  a  breadth  which  does  not 
belong  to  the  mental  state  which  accompanies,  or  leads  to,  the  pro- 
duction of  works  of  beauty  by  the  artist. 

And  yet  it  should  not  surprise  us  that  this  distinction  has  so 
often  been  overlooked;  for  the  theorists  first  follow  the  trend  of 
thought  of  the  uncritical  man,  and  this  uncritical  man  does  not 
naturally  make  the  distinction  referred  to. 

For,  on  the  one  hand,  even  the  least  talented  of  men  has  some 
little  tendency  to  give  part  of  his  strength  to  artistic  creation  in  one 
form  or  another;  the  creative  artist  is  guided  by  what  is  a  truly  racial 
instinct,  which  under  favorable  conditions  will  appear  in  any  man 
who  is  not  defective:  each  of  us  thus  in  the  appreciation  of  beauty 
throws  himself  to  some  degree  into  the  attitude  of  the  creative  artist. 

And,  on  the  other  hand,  the  artist,  when  not  in  creative  mood,  falls 
back  into  the  ranks  of  men  who  keenly  appreciate  beauty  but  who 

1  Cf .  my  MstheHc  Principles,  chap,  i,  "  The  Observer's  Standpoint,"  and 
chap.  Ill,  "The  Artist's  Standpoint." 


THE   RELATIONS   OF  ESTHETICS  419 

are  not  productive  artists;    he  thus  alternately  creates  and  appre- 
ciates, and  with  difficulty  separates  his  diverse  moods. 

We  may  well  consider  these  two  distinguishable  mental  attitudes 
separately. 

a 

In  asking  what  is  the  nature  of  the  experience  which  we  call  the 
sense  of  beauty,  we  are  stating  what  may  well  be  held  to  be  the  most 
important  problem  in  aesthetics  that  is  presented  to  the  psychologist. 

Man  is  practical  before  he  deals  with  theory,  and  his  first  theo- 
retical questionings  are  aroused  by  practical  demands  in  connection 
with  his  failures  to  reach  the  goal  toward  which  he  strives.  The  de- 
velopment of  modern  aesthetic  theory  has  in  the  main  quite  naively 
followed  this  course,  and  we  may  properly  consider  first  the  psycho- 
logical inquiries  which  seem  to  have  the  most  direct  bearing  upon 
practical  questions. 

The  artist  asks  why  his  efforts  so  often  fail,  and  he  is  led  to  inquire 
what  are  the  qualities  in  his  work  which  he  so  often  misses,  but  now 
and  again  gains  -^dth  the  resulting  attainment  of  beauty. 

It  is  thus  that  we  naturally  find  the  sesthetician  appealing  to  the 
psychologist,  asking  him  what  special  types  of  impression  yield 
beauty,  what  special  characteristics  of  our  mental  states  involve  the 
fullest  aesthetic  experience. 

The  psychologist  is  naturally  first  led  to  consider  certain  striking 
relations  found  within  the  beautiful  object  which  impresses  us,  and 
to  inquire  into  the  nature  of  the  psj^chic  functioning  which  is  in- 
volved with  the  impressions  thus  given.  He  thus  comes  to  consider 
the  relations  of  the  lineal  parts  of  pleasing  plane-surface  figures;  and 
the  study  of  these  relations  has  given  to  us  such  investigations  as 
the  notable  ones  of  Fechner  in  respect  to  the  "Golden  Section," 
which  have  been  supplemented  by  the  more  rigid  tests  of  Dr.  Witmer 
and  Doctors  Haines  and  Davies  in  our  own  day.  In  similar  manner 
the  basis  of  the  beauty  found  in  symmetry  and  in  order,  and  the 
problems  related  to  rhythm,  have  been  closely  studied,  especially 
in  late  years  by  Lipps;  and  the  fundamental  principles  of  tonal 
relation,  and  of  melodic  succession,  by  Helmholtz,  Stumpf,  and 
later  writers. 

But  all  these  studies  of  the  striking  characteristics  found  in  the 
object  are  for  the  psychologist  necessarily  involved  with  the  study 
of  the  distinctly  subjective  accompaniments  in  the  sense  of  beauty 
aroused  by  the  objective  forms  thus  brought  to  our  attention,  and 
he  is  led  to  dwell  upon  the  active  part  the  mind  takes  in  connection 
with  aesthetic  appreciation.  We  see  this  tendency  in  Berenson's 
emphasis,  and  perhaps  on  the  whole  over-emphasis,  of  the  import- 
ance of  the  interpretation  of  works  of  art,  in  the  group  of  what  I 
would  call  the  arts  of  sight,  in  terms  of  the  tactile  sensibilities.   But 


420  ^ESTHETICS 

we  see  it  much  more  markedly  in  the  important  studies  of  Lipps, 
who  shows  us  how  far  our  appreciation  of  beauty  in  nature,  and  in 
artistic  products,  is  due  to  the  sympathetic  introjection  of  ourselves 
as  it  were  into  the  object,  —  to  what  he  calls  Einfilhlung. 

But,  broad  as  he  shows  the  applicability  of  this  principle  to  be,  it 
is  clear  that  we  have  not  in  it  the  solution  of  the  fundamental  aesthetic 
problem  with  which  the  psychologist  must  deal  when  appealed  to  by 
the  sesthetician.  For  no  one  would  claim  that  all  of  this  sympathetic 
introjection  —  this  Einfilhlung  —  is  aesthetic :  the  aesthetic  Einfilhl- 
ung is  of  a  special  type.  Nor  to  my  mind  does  it  seem  clearly 
shown  that  there  are  no  sources  of  beauty  which  do  not  involve  this 
introjection,  as  would  be  the  case  if  we  had  reached  in  this  principle 
the  solution  of  the  fundamental  sesthetico-psychologic  problem.  For 
instance,  the  sense  of  beauty  experienced  when  I  look  at  some  one 
bright  star  in  the  deep  blue  of  the  heaven  seems  to  me  to  be  inex- 
plicable in  terms  of  such  introjection. 

All  this  work,  however,  brings  help  to  the  practical  artist  and  to 
the  critic.  They  do  not  acknowledge  it  fully  to-day,  but  year  by  year, 
more  and  more  will  the  influence  of  the  results  of  these  studies  be 
felt  as  they  gain  the  attention  of  thinking  men. 

Nevertheless,  we  cannot  but  face  the  fact  that  the  practical  benefit 
to  be  gained  from  them  is  of  a  negative  sort.  There  is  no  royal  road 
to  the  attainment  of  beauty;  but  the  psychologist  is  able  to  point 
out,  by  the  methods  here  considered,  the  inner  nature  of  certain 
sources  of  beauty ;  thus  teaching  the  artist  how  he  may  avoid  ugliness , 
and  even  indicating  to  him  the  main  direction  in  which  he  may  best 
travel  toward  the  attainment  of  his  goal. 

But,  after  all,  the  relations  thus  discovered  in  the  beautiful  object, 
and  the  related  special  analyses  of  mental  functioning  which  are 
involved  with  our  appreciation  of  beauty,  tell  us  of  but  relatively 
isolated  bits  of  the  broad  realm  of  beauty.  The  objects  which  arouse 
within  us  the  sense  of  beauty  are  most  diverse,  and  equally  diverse 
are  the  modes  of  mental  functioning  connected  with  the  appreciation 
of  their  beauty.  * 

And  this  has  led  to  the  formulation  of  such  principles  as  that  of 
the  "unity  of  manifoldness  "  of  which  Fechner  makes  so  much,  and 
that  of  the  monarchischen  Unterordnung  which  Lipps  has  more  lately 
enunciated. 

It  is  indeed  of  great  interest  to  inquire  why  it  is  that  the  processes 
which  lead  to  the  recognition  of  these  principles  are  so  clearly  defined 
in  many  cases  where  the  sense  of  beauty  is  aroused.  But  very  evi- 
dently these  general  principles,  important  though  they  be  in  them- 

'  Nothing  has  shown  this  more  clearly  than  the  investigations  of  Haines  and 
Davies  in  reference  to  the  Golden  Section  of  which  we  have  spoken  above.  See 
Psychological  Review,  xi,  415. 


THE  RELATIONS   OF   ^ESTHETICS  421 

selves,  are  not  ones  upon  which  we  can  afford  to  rest:  for  clearly 
they  apply  in  very  many  cases  where  beauty  does  not  claim  sway. 

Our  whole  mental  life  exemplifies  the  unification  of  the  manifold, 
and  monarchic  subordination,  whether  the  processes  be  aesthetic  or 
not.  It  does  not  suffice  us  to  show,  what  is  thus  shown,  that  the 
aesthetic  states  conform  with  conditions  of  our  mental  life  that 
have  a  broad  significance,  although  it  is  of  great  importance  to 
demonstrate  the  fact:  for  our  mental  functioning  in  the  apprecia- 
tion of  beauty  appears  thus  as  in  truth  an  important  type,  but 
for  aU  that  but  a  special  and  peculiar  type  of  the  functioning  which 
we  thus  bring  into  prominence. 

The  problem  then  remains,  what  is  the  special  nature  of  this 
functioning  which  yields  to  us  the  sense  of  beauty? 

And  here  in  my  view  we  have  the  problem  which  is  of  prime 
importance  to  aesthetics  to-day,  and  which  psychology  alone  can 
answer;  namely,  what  is  the  characteristic  that  differentiates  the 
sense  of  beauty  from  all  other  of  our  mental  states?  Until  this 
question  is  answered,  all  else  must  seem  of  secondary  importance 
from  the  standpoint  of  theoretical  psychology,  however  important 
other  forms  of  inquiry  may  be  from  a  practical  point  of  view. 

When  the  psychologist  turns  his  attention  to  this  problem,  he 
at  once  perceives  that  he  is  unable  to  limit  his  inquiry  to  the  experi- 
ence of  the  technically  trained  artist,  or  even  to  that  of  the  man  of 
culture  who  gives  close  attention  to  aesthetic  appreciation. 

Beauty  is  experienced  by  all  men.  But  beauty  is  very  clearly  of 
varied  types,  and  the  sense  of  beauty  is  evidently  called  out  by 
impressions  of  most  varied  nature;  but  the  fields  of  what  is  considered 
beautiful  by  different  people  so  far  overlap  that  we  can  rest  assured 
that  we  all  refer  to  an  experience  of  the  same  characteristic  mental 
state  when  we  proclaim  the  existence  of  beauty;  for  when  we  by 
general  agreement  use  a  special  term  as  descriptive  of  an  objective 
impression,  we  do  so  because  this  impression  excites  in  us  certain 
more  or  less  specific  mental  states;  and  when  different  people  use 
the  same  term  in  reference  to  objects  of  diverse  nature,  we  are  wont 
to  assume,  and  are  in  general  correct  in  assuming,  that  these  objects 
affect  these  different  people  in  approximately  the  same  way. 

It  seems  probable,  therefore,  that  if  the  child,  who  has  learned  how 
to  apply  words  from  his  elders,  speaks  of  having  a  beautiful  time  at 
his  birthday  party;  and  if  the  grown  man  speaks  of  a  beautiful  day; 
and  if  the  pathologist  speaks  of  his  preparation  of  morbid  tissue  as 
beautiful;  and  if  the  artist  or  connoisseur  speaks  of  the  beauty  of 
a  picture,  a  statue,  a  work  of  architecture,  a  poem,  a  symphony; 
then  the  word  beauty  must  be  used  to  describe  a  certain  special  mental 
state  which  is  aroused  in  different  people  by  very  diverse  objective 
impressions. 


422  AESTHETICS 

This  view  is  strengthened  when  we  consider  that  the  apphcation 
of  the  term  by  individuals  changes  as  they  develop  naturally  or  by 
processes  of  education;  and  that  the  standards  of  beauty  alter  in 
like  manner  in  a  race  from  generation  to  generation  as  it  advances 
in  its  development. 

We  must  then  look  for  the  essence  of  beauty  in  some  quality  of 
our  mental  states  which  is  called  up  by  different  objective  impres- 
sions in  different  people,  and  under  diverse  conditions  by  different 
objects  at  different  times  in  the  same  individual. 

Search  for  such  a  quality  has  led  not  a  few  psychologists  to  look 
to  pleasure  as  the  quality  of  our  mental  states  which  is  most  likely 
to  meet  our  demand.  It  is  true  that  the  consideration  of  pleasure 
as  of  the  essence  of  the  sense  of  beauty  has  not  often  been  seriously 
carried  out ;  apparently  because  so  many  of  what  we  speak  of  as  our 
most  vivid  pleasures  appear  as  non-sesthetic;  and  because  pleasure 
is  recognized  to  be  markedly  evanescent,  while  beauty  is  thought  of 
as  at  least  relatively  permanent. 

It  is  true,  also,  that  there  is  a  hesitancy  in  using  the  word  pleasure 
in  this  connection;  many  writers  preferring  the  less  definite  word 
"feeling"  in  English,  and  "gefiihl"  in  German.  But  by  a  large 
number  of  psychologists  the  words  pleasure  and  feeling  are  used  as 
synonyms;  and  those  who,  with  me,  agree  that  what  we  loosely  call 
feeling  is  broader  than  mere  pleasure,  must  note  that  it  is  the  pleas- 
urable aspect  alone  of  what  is  called  "feeling"  that  is  essentially 
related  to  our  experience  of  the  sense  of  beauty. 

All  of  us  agree,  in  any  event,  that  the  sense  of  beauty  is  highly 
pleasant;  and, in  fact,  most  of  our  aestheticians  have  come  to  assume 
tacitly  in  their  writings  that  the  field  of  aesthetics  must  be  treated 
as  a  field  of  pleasure-getting;  and  this  whether  or  not  they  attempt 
to  indicate  the  relation  of  pleasure-getting  to  the  sense  of  beauty. 

The  suggestion  that  pleasure  of  a  certain  type  is  of  the  essence  of 
beauty  seems  the  more  likely  to  prove  to  be  satisfactory  when  we 
consider  that  pleasure  is  universally  acknowledged  to  be  the  con- 
tradictory opposite  of  pain;  and  that  we  have  in  ugliness,  which  is 
always  unpleasant,  a  contradictory  opposite  of  beauty.^ 

Clearly  then  it  behooves  the  psychologist  to  give  to  the  sesthetician 
an  account  of  the  nature  of  pleasure  which  shall  be  compatible  with 
the  pleasurable  nature  of  the  sense  of  beauty;  and  which  shall  either 
explain  the  nature  of  this  sense  of  beauty  in  terms  of  pleasure,  or 
explain  the  nature  of  pleasure  in  a  manner  which  shall  throw  light 
upon  the  nature  of  this  sense  of  beauty  to  which  pleasure  is  so  indis- 
solubly  attached. 

'  It  is  of  course  agreed  that  beauty  and  ugliness  may  be  held  together  in  a 
complex  impression:  but  in  such  cases  the  beauty  and  the  ugliness  are  inherent 
in  diverse  elements  of  the  complex. 


THE  RELATIONS  OF   ESTHETICS  423 

The  aesthetician  thus  demands  urgently  of  the  psychologist  an 
analysis  of  the  nature  of  pleasure;  and  an  analysis  of  this  so- 
called  "feeling,"  which  shall  show  the  relation  between  the  two 
experiences. 

Concerning  the  latter  problem  I  hope  some  day  to  have  something 
to  say. 

Those  of  you  who  happen  to  be  familiar  with  my  published  works 
will  realize  that  my  efforts  in  this  field  in  the  past  have  been  given 
largely  to  the  study  of  the  former  problem.  My  own  view  may  be 
succinctly  stated  thus. 

While  all  aesthetic  experiences  are  pleasant,  very  evidently  much 
that  we  call  pleasant  is  not  aesthetic.  We  must  look  then  for  some 
special  differentiation  of  aesthetic  pleasure,  and  this  I  find  in  its 
relative  permanency. 

This  view  is  led  up  to  by  a  preliminary  study  of  the  psychological 
nature  of  pleasure. 

Pleasure  I  find  to  be  one  phase  of  a  general  quality  —  Pleasure- 
Pain —  which,  under  proper  conditions,  may  inhere  in  any  emphasis 
within  the  field  of  attention,  or,  to  use  more  common  language,  may 
belong  to  any  element  of  attention. 

Now  pleasure,  as  we  have  said,  is  notably  evanescent,  but  this 
does  not  preclude  the  existence  of  pleasurable  states  of  attention 
which  are  relatively  permanent.  This  permanency  may  be  given  by 
the  shifting  of  attention  from  one  pleasurable  element  to  another; 
by  the  summation  of  very  moderate  pleasures,  etc.,  etc. 

Any  pleasant  psychic  element  may  become  an  element  of  an 
aesthetic  complex :  and  any  psychic  complex  which  displays  a  relative 
permanency  of  pleasure  is  in  that  fact  aesthetic.  Our  aesthetic  states 
are  those  in  which  many  pleasant  elements  are  combined  to  produce 
a  relative  permanency  of  pleasure. 

Our  "non-aesthetic  pleasures,"  so  called,  are  those  states  which 
have  been  experienced  in  the  past  as  vividly  pleasant,  and  to  which 
the  name  pleasure  has  become  indissolubly  attached:  but  they  are 
states  which  do  not  produce  a  relatively  permanent  pleasure  in 
revival;  and  correctly  speaking,  are  not  pleasures  at  the  moment 
when  they  are  described  as  such,  and  at  the  same  time  as  non- 
aesthetic. 

I  am  glad  to  feel  that  this  view  of  mine  is  not  discrepant  from  that 
of  Dr.  Santayana,  as  given  in  quite  different  terms  in  his  book  en- 
titled The  Sense  of  Beauty.  For  what  is  relatively  permanent  has 
the  quality  which  I  call  realness;  and  that  in  experience  which  has 
realness  we  tend  to  objectify.  Hence  it  is  quite  natural  to  find  Dr. 
Santayana  defining  beauty  as  objectified  pleasure. 

You  will  not  blame  me  I  believe  for  thinking  that  my  own  defini- 
tion cuts  down  closer  to  the  root  of  the  matter  than  Dr.  Santayana 's. 


424  AESTHETICS 

But  if  this  theory  of  mine  is  found  wanting,  the  j£sthetician  will 
not  cease  to  call  upon  the  psychologist  for  some  other  which  shall 
meet  the  demands  of  introspection;  and  which  shall  accord  with  our 
experiences  of  the  sense  of  beauty,  which  in  all  their  wealth  of  impres- 
sion the  sesthetician  offers  to  the  psychologist  as  data  for  the  labor- 
ious study  asked  of  him. 

Before  leaving  this  subject  I  may  perhaps  be  allowed  to  call 
attention  to  the  fact  that  the  theoretical  view,  which  places  the  essence 
of  the  sense  of  beauty  in  pleasure-getting,  if  it  prove  to  be  true,  is 
not  without  such  practical  applications  as  are  so  properly  demanded 
in  our  time.  For  if  this  view  is  correct,  it  teaches' to  the  critic  a  lesson 
of  sympathetic  tolerance;  for  he  learns  from  it  that  the  sources  from 
which  the  sense  of  beauty  are  derived  differ  very  markedly  in  people 
of  diverse  types:  and  it  warns  him  also  against  the  danger  of  an 
artificial  limitation  of  his  own  a)sthetic  sense,  which  will  surely 
result  unless  he  carefully  avoids  the  narrowing  of  his  interests. 

It  teaches  further  that  there  is  no  validity  in  the  distinction 
between  fine  art  and  aesthetics  on  the  one  hand,  and  beauty  on  the 
other,  on  the  ground,  commonly  accepted  by  the  highly  trained 
artist  and  connoisseur,  that  a  work  of  art  may  deal  with  what  is  not 
beautiful. 

For  it  appears  that  while  the  sense  of  beauty  is  the  same  for  each 
of  us,  the  objects  which  call  it  out  are  in  some  measure  different  for 
each. 

Now  it  happens  naturally  that  the  objects  which  arouse  the  sense 
of  beauty  in  a  large  proportion  of  men  of  culture  get  the  word  beauty 
firmly  attached  to  them  in  common  speech. 

But  under  the  view  here  maintained,  it  must  be  that  the  highly 
trained  artist. or  critic  will  pass  beyond  these  commoner  men,  and 
find  his  sense  of  beauty  aroused  by  objects  and  objective  relations 
quite  different  from  those  which  arouse  the  sense  of  beauty  in  the 
commoner  man;  so  that  often  he  may  deal  with  the  beauty  of 
elements  in  connection  with  which  beauty  is  unknown  to  the  com- 
moner man,  and  even  with  elements  which  arouse  a  sense  of  ugliness 
in  the  commoner  man;  while  on  the  other  hand  the  objects  which 
the  commoner  man  signalizes  as  most  beautiful,  and  which  are  cur- 
rently so  called,  may  not  arouse  in  the  trained  artist  or  critic  the 
sense  of  beauty  which  is  now  aroused  in  him  by  effects  of  broader 
nature,  and  of  less  common  experience. 

The  critic  and  the  skilled  artist  thus  often  find  their  aesthetic  sense 
aroused  no  longer  by  the  objects  to  which  the  word  beauty  has  by  com- 
mon consent  come  to  be  attached ;  although  with  the  commoner  man  he 
still  uses  the  word  beauty  as  descriptive  of  the  object  which  arouses 
the  aesthetic  thrill  in  the  mass  of  normally  educated  men.    He  may 


THE  RELATIONS  OF   ESTHETICS  425 

even  find  his  aesthetic  sense  aroused  by  what  the  common  man  calls 
ugly;  although  it  is  for  himself  really  beautiful.  And  he  comes  thus 
quite  improperly  to  think  of  the  highest  art  as  in  a  measure  inde- 
pendent of  what  he  calls  "mere  beauty."  What  he  has  a  right  to 
say,  however,  is  merely  this,  that  the  highest  art  deals  with  sources 
of  beauty  which  are  not  appreciated  by  even  the  generally  well- 
cultivated  man. 


I  have  dwelt,  perhaps,  too  long  on  the  psychological  problems 
presented  when  the  psychologist  attempts  to  describe  to  the  sesthet- 
ician  the  nature  of  the  experience  of  one  who  appreciates  beauty; 
and  have  left  perhaps  too  little  time  for  the  consideration  of  the 
problems  presented  when  he  is  asked  to  consider  the  nature  of  the 
experience  of  the  artist  who  creates. 

The  man  who  finds  strongly  developed  within  him  the  creative 
tendency,  is  wont,  when  he  turns  to  theory,  to  lay  emphasis  upon 
expression  as  of  the  essence  of  beauty. 

It  is,  of  course,  to  be  granted  that  the  process  of  Einfilhlung,  — 
of  introjection,  —  above  referred  to,  leads  us  to  find  a  source  of 
beauty  in  the  vague  imagination  of  ourselves  as  doing  what  others 
have  done;  and  we  may  take  great  aesthetic  delight  in  reading, 
through  his  work,  the  mind  of  the  man  who  has  created  the  object 
of  beauty  for  us.  But  evidently,  when  we  lay  stress  upon  this  intro- 
jection, we  are  dealing  with  the  appreciation  of  beauty,  and  not  with 
the  force  which  leads  to  its  production. 

Just  as  clearly  is  it  impossible  to  hold  that  expression  is  of  the 
essence  of  the  making  of  beauty.  For  expressiveness  is  involved  in 
all  of  man's  creative  activity,  much  of  which  has  no  relation  what- 
ever to  the  aesthetic.  The  expression  of  the  character  of  the  genius 
of  the  inventor  of  a  cotton  loom,  or  of  the  successful  leader  of  an 
army  in  a  bloody  battle,  excites  our  interest  and  wonder;  but  the 
expression  of  his  character  as  read  in  the  result  accomplished  does 
not  constitute  it  a  work  of  beauty. 

I  speak  of  this  point  at  this  length  because  in  my  opinion  views 
of  the  nature  of  that  here  objected  to  could  not  have  been  upheld 
by  such  men  as  Bosanquet  and  Veron  had  they  kept  clear  the  dis- 
tinction referred  to  above  between  the  experience  of  one  who  ap- 
preciates beauty,  and  the  experience  of  the  creative  artist;  and 
especially  because  the  teaching  of  the  doctrine  thus  combated  is 
wont  to  lead  the  artist  whose  cry  is  "  Art  for  Art's  sake"  to  excessive 
self-satisfaction,  and  to  lack  of  restraint  which  leads  to  failure.^ 

*  In  order  to  avoid  misunderstanding,  I  may  say  here  that  notwithstanding 
these  remarks  I  am  in  full  sympathy  with  the  artist  who  thus  expresses  himself, 
as  will  presently  appear  clear. 


426  ESTHETICS 

The  strong  hold  which  this  theory  has  in  many  minds  has  its  value, 
however,  in  the  emphasis  of  the  fact  that  aesthetic  creation  is  due 
to  impulses  which  are  born  of  innate  instincts  expressing  them- 
selves in  the  production  of  works  of  beauty.  And  if  this  be  so,  we  see 
how  true  it  must  be  that  each  of  us  must  have  in  him  some  measure 
of  this  instinct;  and  that  the  appearance  of  its  appropriate  impulses 
should  not  mislead  us,  and  induce  us  to  devote  our  lives  to  the 
worship  of  the  Muses,  unless  we  become  convinced  that  no  other  work 
can  adequately  express  the  best  that  is  in  us. 

But  the  true  artist  is  not  troubled  by  such  questionings.  He  finds 
himself  carried  away  by  what  is  a  true  passion;  by  what  is  instinct- 
ive and  not  ratiocinative. 

The  fact  that  the  artist  is  thus  impelled  by  what  may  well  be  called 
the  "art  instinct"  is  one  he  could  only  have  learned  from  the  psy- 
chologist, or  when  in  introspective  mood  he  became  a  psychologist 
himself;  and  it  carries  with  it  corollaries  of  great  value,  which  the 
psychologist  alone  can  elucidate. 

It  teaches  the  artist,  for  instance,  that  his  success  must  be  deter- 
mined by  the  measure  of  this  instinct  that  is  developed  within  him; 
that  he  must  allow  himself  to  be  led  by  this  instinct;  that  his  best 
work  will  be  his  "spontaneous"  work.  This,  of  course,  is  very  far 
from  saying  that  he  cannot  gain  by  training;  but  it  does  mean  that 
he  must  learn  to  treat  this  training  as  his  tool;  that  he  must  not 
trust  overmuch  to  his  ratiocinative  work,  the  result  of  which  must 
be  assimilated  by,  and  become  part  of,  his  impulsive  nature,  if  he  is 
to  be  a  master. 

An  artist  is  one  in  whom  is  highly  developed  the  instinct  which 
leads  him  to  create  objects  that  arouse  the  sense  of  beauty.  The 
expression  of  this  instinct  marks  his  appropriate  functioning.  He 
may  incidentally  do  many  useful  things,  and  produce  results  apart 
from  his  special  aptitude;  but  as  an  artist  his  work  is  solely  and 
completely  bound  up  in  the  production  of  works  of  beauty. 

We  naturally  ask  here  what  may  be  the  function  in  life  of  the 
expressions  of  such  an  instinct  as  we  have  been  studying,  and  this 
leads  us  to  consider  a  point  of  more  than  psychological  interest, 
and  turns  our  thought  to  our  second  division. 

II.  The  Relation  of  ^Esthetics  to  Philosophy 

For  while  the  science  of  psychology  must  guide,  it  can  never  dom- 
inate the  thought  of  the  philosopher  who  strives  to  gain  a  broad  view 
of  the  world  of  experience;  and,  as  will  appear  below,  the  sesthetician 
calls  upon  the  philosopher  for  aid  which  the  psychologist  as  such 
cannot  give. 


.    THE   RELATIONS   OF  ESTHETICS  427 

a 

In  approacMng  this  subject  we  may  take  at  the  start  what  we  may 
call  the  broadly  philosophical  view,  and  may  consider  the  question 
raised  immediately  above,  where  we  ask  what  may  be  the  function 
in  life  of  the  art  instinct,  and  what  the  significance  of  the  aesthetic 
production  to  which  its  expression  leads. 

We,  in  our  day,  are  still  strongly  influenced  by  the  awakening  of 
interest  in  the  problems  of  organic  development  with  which  Darwin's 
name  is  identified,  and  thus  naturally  look  upon  this  problem  from 
a  genetic  point  of  view;  from  which,  to  my  mind,  artistic  expression 
appears,  as  I  have  elsewhere  argued  at  length,  as  one  of  nature's 
means  to  enforce  social  consolidation.  But  it  is  possible  that  we 
are  led,  by  the  present-day  interest  above  spoken  of,  to  over- 
emphasize the  importance  of  the  processes  of  the  unfolding  of  our 
capacities,  and  it  is  not  improbable  that  those  who  follow  us,  less 
blinded  by  the  brilliancy  of  the  achievement  of  the  evolutionists, 
may  be  able  to  look  deeper  than  we  can  into  the  essence  of  the 
teleological  problem  thus  raised. 

That  art  is  worthy  for  art's  sake  is  the  conviction  of  a  large  body 
of  artists,  who  labor  in  their  chosen  work  often  with  a  truly  martyr- 
like self-abnegation;  and  as  an  artist  I  find  myself  heartily  in  sym- 
pathy with  this  attitude.  But  aesthetics  looks  to  philosophy  for 
some  account  of  this  artistic  reXos,  which  shall  harmonize  the  artist's 
effort  with  that  of  mankind  in  general,  from  whom  the  artist  all  too 
often  feels  himself  cut  off  by  an  impassable  gulf. 

The  study  of  aesthetics  by  the  philosopher  from  the  genetic  stand- 
point has,  however,  already  brought  to  our  attention  some  facts 
which  are  both  significant  and  helpful. 

It  has  shown  us  how  slow  and  hesitant  have  been  the  steps  in  the 
development  of  aesthetic  accomplishment  and  appreciation  in  the 
past,  and  how  dependent  these  steps  have  been  upon  economic  con- 
ditions. This  on  the  one  hand  arouses  in  us  a  demand  for  a  fuller 
study  of  the  relations  of  the  artistic  to  the  other  activities  of  men; 
and  on  the  other  hand  is  a  source  of  encouragement  to  critic  and 
artist  alike,  each  of  whom  in  every  age  is  apt  to  over-emphasize  the 
artistic  failures  of  his  time,  and  to  minimize  the  importance  of  its 
artistic  accomplishment. 

This  genetic  study  has  a  further  value  in  the  guidance  of  our 
critical  judgment,  in  that  it  shows  us  that  the  artistic  tendencies 
of  our  time  are  but  steps  in  what  is  a  continuous  process  of  develop- 
ment. It  shows  us  arts  which  have  differentiated  in  the  past,  and 
teaches  us  to  look  for  further  artistic  differentiations  of  the  arts  in 
the  future;  thus  leading  us  to  critical  conclusions  of  no  little  im- 
portance. This  consideration  seems  to  me  to  be  of  sufficient  interest 
to  warrant  our  dwelling  upon  it  a  little  at  length. 


428  ESTHETICS 

The  arts  of  greatest  importance  in  our  time  may  well  be  divided 
into  the  arts  of  hearing  (that  is,  literature,  poetry,  music),  and  the 
arts  of  sight  (that  is,  architecture,  sculpture,  painting,  and  the 
graphic  arts). 

These  diverse  groups  of  arts  were  differentiated  long  before  any 
age  of  which  we  have  a  shadow  of  record.  But  many  animals  display 
what  seem  to  be  rudimentary  art  instincts,  in  which  rhythmical  move- 
ment (which  is  to  be  classed  as  an  art  of  sight)  and  tonal  accompani- 
ment are  invariably  combined  —  as  they  are  also  in  the  dance  and 
song  of  the  savage;  and  this  fact  would  seem  to  indicate  that  in  the 
earliest  times  of  man's  rise  from  savagery  the  differentiation  between 
the  arts  of  sight  and  the  arts  of  hearing  was  at  least  very  incom- 
plete. 

But  leaving  such  surmises,  we  may  consider  the  arts  of  sight  and 
the  arts  of  hearing  in  themselves.  We  see  them  still  in  a  measure 
bound  together;  for  many  an  artist,  for  instance,  devotes  his  life 
to  the  making  of  paintings  which  "tell  a  story,"  and  many  a  poet 
to  the  production  of  "word-pictures." 

In  general,  however,  it  may  be  said  that  the  arts  of  hearing  and 
the  arts  of  sight  express  themselves  in  totally  different  languages, 
so  to  speak,  and  they  have  thus  differentiated  because  each  can  give 
a  special  form  of  aesthetic  delight. 

Turning  to  the  consideration  of  each  great  group,  we  note  that 
the  arts  of  sight  have  become  clearly  differentiated  on  lines  which 
enable  us  to  group  them  broadly  as  the  graphic  arts,  painting, 
sculpture,  and  architecture.  Each  of  these  latter  has  become  im- 
portant in  itself,  and  has  separated  itself  from  the  others,  just  so 
far  as  it  has  shown  that  it  can  arouse  the  sense  of  beauty  in  a  man- 
ner which  its  kindred  arts  of  sight  cannot  approach.  It  is  true  that 
all  the  arts  of  sight  hold  together  more  closely  than  do  the  arts  of 
sight,  as  such,  with  the  arts  of  hearing,  as  such.  But  it  is  equally 
clear  that  the  bond  between  the  several  arts  of  sight  was  closer 
in  earlier  times  than  it  is  to-day,  in  the  fact  that  modeled  paint- 
ing, and  colored  sculpture,  were  common  media  of  artistic  expres- 
sion among  the  ancients,  the  latter  being  still  conventional  even  so 
late  as  in  the  times  of  the  greatest  development  of  art  among  the 
Greeks. 

But  the  modern  has  learned  that  in  painting  and  graphics  the 
artist  can  gain  a  special  source  of  beauty  of  color  and  line  which  he 
is  able  to  gain  with  less  distinctness  when  he  models  the  surface  upon 
which  he  works :  and  the  experience  of  the  ages  has  gradually  taught 
the  sculptor  once  for  all  that  he  in  his  own  special  medium  is  able 
to  gain  a  special  source  of  beauty  of  pure  form  which  no  other  arts 
can  reach,  and  that  this  special  type  of  beauty  cannot  be  brought 
into  as  great  emphasis  when  he  colors  his  modeled  forms. 


THE  RELATIONS  OF  ESTHETICS  429 

In  my  view  we  may  well  state,  as  a  valid  critical  principle,  that, 
other  things  being  equal,  in  any  art  the  artist  does  best  who  presents 
in  his  chosen  medium  a  source  of  beauty  which  cannot  be  as  well 
presented  by  any  other  art.  That  this  principle  is  appreciated  and 
widely  accepted  (although  implicitly  rather  than  explicitly)  is 
indicated  by  the  unrationalized  objection  of  the  cultivated  critic  in 
our  day  to  colored  sculpture  or  to  modeled  painting,  and  in  a  more 
special  direction  to  the  use  of  body-color  in  aquarelle  work.  The 
objection  in  all  cases  is  apparently  to  the  fact  that  the  artist  fails  to 
bring  into  prominence  that  type  of  beauty  which  his  medium  can 
present  as  no  other  medium  can. 

Personally  I  have  no  objection  to  raise  to  a  recombination  of  the 
arts  of  sight,  provided  a  fuller  sense  of  beauty  can  thereby  be 
reached.  But  it  is  clear  that  this  recombination  becomes  more  and 
more  difficult  as  the  ages  of  development  pass;  and  I  believe  the 
principle  of  critical  judgment  above  enunciated  is  valid,  based  as 
it  is  upon  the  inner  sense  of  cultivated  men. 

Better  than  attempts  to  recombine  the  already  differentiated 
arts  of  sight  are  attempts  to  use  them  in  conjunction,  so  that  our 
shiftings  of  attention  from  one  type  of  beauty  to  another  may  carry 
with  them  more  permanent  and  fuller  sesthetic  effects ;  and  such 
attempts  we  see  common  to-day  in  the  conjunction  of  architecture 
and  of  sculpture  and  of  painting,  in  our  private  and  public  galleries, 
in  which  are  collected  together  works  of  the  arts  of  sight. 

Now  if  we  turn  to  the  consideration  of  the  arts  of  hearing,  we  find 
a  correspondence  which  leads  to  certain  suggestions  of  no  little 
importance  to  the  critical  analyst  in  our  day. 

The  arts  of  hearing  have  become  differentiated  on  lines  which 
enable  us  to  group  them  broadly  as  rhetoric,  poetry  and  literature, 
and  music.  Each  has  become  important  in  itself,  and  has  gradually 
separated  itself  from  the  others;  —  and  this  just  so  far  as  it  has 
shown  that  it  can  arouse  in  men,  in  a  special  and  peculiar  manner, 
the  sense  of  beauty. 

It  is  true,  as  with  the  arts  of  sight,  that  the  special  arts  of  hearing 
still  hold  well  together. 

But  in  relatively  very  modern  times  music,  having  discovered  a 
written  language  of  its  own,  has  differentiated  very  distinctly  from 
the  other  arts  of  hearing.  Men  have  discovered  that  'pure  music 
can  arouse  in  a  special  manner  the  sense  of  beauty,  and  can  bring  to 
us  a  form  of  sesthetic  delight  which  no  other  art  can  as  well  give. 

Poetry  has  long  been  written  which  is  not  to  be  sung;  and  it  has 
gained  much  in  freedom  of  development  in  that  fact. 

Music  in  our  modern  times  is  composed  by  the  greatest  masters 
for  its  own  intrinsic  worth,  and  not  as  of  old  as  a  mere  accompani- 


430  ESTHETICS 

merit  of  the  spoken  word  of  the  poet;  the  existence  of  the  works 
of  Bach,  to  mention  no  others,  tells  of  the  value  of  this  differentiation. 

And  here  I  think  we  may  apply  with  justice  the  principle  of  criticism 
above  presented.  The  poet  and  the  musician  each  do  their  best  work, 
other  things  being  equal,  when  they  emphasize  the  forms  of  beauty 
which  their  several  arts  alone  can  give.  We  have  here  in  my  view 
a  rational  ground  for  the  repulsion  many  of  us  feel  for  the  so-called 
"programme  music"  of  our  day. 

Music  and  literature  of  the  highest  types  nowadays  present 
sources  of  beauty  of  very  diverse  character,  and  any  effort  to  make 
one  subsidiary  to  the  other  is  likely  to  lessen  the  aesthetic  worth  of 
each,  and  of  the  combination. 

Here  again  I  may  say  that  I  have  no  objection  to  raise  to  a  recom- 
bination of  the  arts  of  hearing,  provided  a  fuller  sense  of  beauty 
can  thereby  be  reached.  But  this  recombination  becomes  year  by 
3^ear  more  difficult  as  the  several  arts  become  more  clearly  differen- 
tiated, and  must  in  my  view  soon  reach  its  limit. 

The  opera  of  to-day  attempts  such  a  recombination,  but  does  so 
either  to  the  detriment  of  the  musical  or  of  the  literary  constituent; 
that  is  clear  when  we  consider  the  musical  ineptitude  of  such  operas 
as  deal  with  a  finely  developed  drama,  and  the  literary  crudeness  of 
the  plot-interest  in  Wagner's  very  best  works.  Such  a  consideration 
makes  very  clear  to  us  how  much  each  of  the  great  divisions  of  the 
arts  of  hearing  has  gained  by  their  differentiation,  and  by  their  inde- 
pendent development. 

Here  as  with  the  arts  of  sight  we  may,  in  my  view,  hope  for 
better  eesthetic  results  from  the  development  of  each  of  the  differ- 
entiated arts  in  conjunction;  rather  from  the  persistent  attempt  to 
recombine  them,  with  the  almost  certain  result  that  the  aesthetic 
value  of  each  will  be  reduced. 

h 

But  aesthetics  demands  more  of  philosophy  than  an  account  of  the 
genesis  of  art,  with  all  the  valuable  lessons  that  this  involves.  It  de- 
mands, rightly,  that  it  be  given  a  place  of  honor  in  any  system  which 
claims  to  give  us  a  rationalized  scheme  of  the  universe  of  experience. 

The  aesthetician  tells  the  philosopher  that  he  'cannot  but  ask 
himself  what  significance  aesthetic  facts  have  for  his  pluralism,  or 
for  his  monism.  He  claims  that  this  question  is  too  often  overlooked 
entirely  or  too  lightly  considered;  but  that  it  must  be  satisfactorily 
answered  if  the  system-maker  is  to  find  acceptance  of  his  view. 
And  in  the  attempt  to  answer  this  and  kindred  questions,  the  aesthet- 
ician is  not  without  hope  that  no  inconsiderable  light  may  be  thrown 
by  the  philosopher  upon  the  solution  of  the  problems  of  aesthetics 
itself. 


THE  RELATIONS  OF   .ESTHETICS  431 

Nor  are  the  problems  of  aesthetics  without  relation  to  pure  meta- 
physic.  The  existence  of  aesthetic  standards  must  be  considered  by 
the  metaphysician,  and  these  standards,  with  those  of  logic  and  ethics, 
must  be  treated  by  him  as  data  for  the  study  of  ontological 
problems. 

But  beyond  this,  aesthetics  cries  out  for  special  aid  from  the 
ontologist.  What,  he  asks,  is  the  significance  of  our  standards  of 
aesthetic  appreciation?  What  the  inner  nature  of  that  which  we  call 
the  real  of  beauty?  What  its  relation  with  the  real  of  goodness 
and  the  real  of  truth? 

From  a  practical  standpoint  this  last-mentioned  question  is  of 
special  import  at  this  time.  For  the  world  of  art  has  for  centuries 
been  torn  asunder  by  the  contention  of  the  aesthetic  realists  and  their 
opponents. 

That,  in  its  real  essence,  beauty  is  truth,  and  truth  beauty,  is 
a  claim  which  has  often  been,  and  is  still  heard;  and  it  is  a  claim 
which  must  finally  be  adjudicated  by  the  metaphysician  who  deals 
wth  the  nature  of  the  real. 

The  practical  importance  of  the  solution  of  this  problem  is  brought 
home  forcibly  to  those  who,  like  myself,  seem  to  see  marked  aesthetic 
deterioration  in  the  work  of  those  artists  who  have  been  led  to  listen 
to  the  claims  of  aesthetic  realism;  who  learn  to  strive  for  the  expres- 
sion of  truth,  thinking  thus  certainly  to  gain  beauty. 

That  many  great  artists  have  announced  themselves  as  aesthetic 
realists  shows  how  powerfully  the  claims  of  the  doctrine  appeal  to 
them.  But  one  who  studies  the  artistic  work  of  Leonardo,  for  in- 
stance, cannot  but  believe  that  he  was  a  great  artist  notwithstanding 
his  theoretical  belief,  and  cannot  but  believe  that  all  others  of  his 
way  of  thinking,  so  far  as  they  are  artists,  are  such  because  in  them 
genius  has  overridden  their  dogmatic  thought. 

It  is  clearly  not  without  significance  that  the  world  of  values  is 
by  common  consent  held  to  be  covered  by  the  categories  of  the  True, 
the  Good,  and  the  Beautiful.  This  common  consent  seems  surely 
to  imply  that  each  of  the  three  is  independent  of  the  other  two, 
although  aU  are  bound  together  in  one  group.  And  if  this  is  true,  then 
the  claim  of  the  aesthetic  realist  can  surely  not  be  correct. 

But  this  claim  will  not  be  overthrown  by  any  reference  to  such 
a  generalization  as  that  above  mentioned.  The  claim  of  the  aesthetic 
realist  is  based  upon  what  he  feels  to  be  clear  evidence  founded  upon 
experience;  and  he  cannot  be  answered  unless  we  are  able  to  show 
him  what  is  the  basis  foT  his  ready  conviction  that  truth  and  beauty 
are  one  and  identical;  and  what  is  the  true  relation  between  the 
True,  the  Good,  and  the  Beautiful.  And  these  problems,  which  are 
in  our  day  of  vital  importance  to  the  artist,  the  philosopher  alone 
can  answer. 


432  ESTHETICS 

In  my  view  some  aid  in  the  solution  of  this  problem  may  be  gained 
from  the  examination  of  the  meaning  of  our  terms.  From  this  study 
I  feel  convinced  that  we  must  hold  that  when  we  speak  of  the  True, 
and  the  Good,  and  the  Beautiful,  as  mutually  exclusive  as  above, 
we  use  the  term  "true"  in  a  narrow  sense.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
True  is  often  used  in  a  broader  sense,  as  equivalent  to  the  Real. 

This  being  so  we  may  say 

That  the  Beautiful  is  the  Real  as  discovered  in  the  world  of  im- 
pression; the  relatively  permanent  pleasure  which  gives  us  the  sense 
of  beauty  being  the  most  stable  characteristic  of  those  parts  of  the 
field  of  impression  which  interest  us  we  may  also  assent 

That  the  Good  is  the  Real  as  discovered  in  the  world  of  expression, 
that  is,  of  impulse,  which  is  due  to  the  inhibited  capacity  for  expres- 
sion, and  the  reaction  of  the  self  in  its  efforts  to  break  down  the 
inhibition.    And  in  the  same  way  we  may  conclude 

That  the  True  (using  the  term  in  the  narrow  sense)  is  the  Real 
as  discovered  in  the  realm  of  experience  exclusive  of  impression  or 
expression. 


The  Real 
or 

The  True 
(in  the  broad  sense 
of  the  term) 


The  Real  of  Impression  —  The  Beautiful 

The  Real  of  Expression  —  The  Good 

The  Real  in  realms         —  The  True 
exclusive  of  a  and  ft  (in  the  narrower 

sense  of  the  term) 


That  the  Beautiful  is  part  of  the  Real,  that  is,  is  always  the 
True,  using  the  term  true  in  the  broader  sense,  is  not  questioned:  and 
that,  in  my  view,  is  the  theoretical  truth  recognized  by  the  aesthetic 
realists.  But  in  practice  the  aesthetic  realist  maintains  that  the 
beautiful  is  always  the  true,  using  the  term  true  in  the  narrow  sense, 
and  in  this,  in  my  view,  lies  his  error. 

And  if  the  relation  of  the  beautiful  to  the  true  demands  the 
attention  of  the  philosopher,  equally  so  does  the  relation  of  the 
beautiful  to  the  good.  As  I  look  upon  it,  all  of  the  true  (using  the 
term  as  above  explained  in  the  narrow  sense)  and  all  of  the  good, 
so  far  as  either  involve  relatively  permanent  pleasure  of  impression, 
are  possible  elements  of  beauty.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  it  seems  clear 
that  neither  the  true  (still  using  the  term  in  the  nari'ower  sense) ,  nor 
the  good,  is  necessarily  pleasing,  but  may  be  unpleasant,  and  there- 
fore either  of  them  may  be  an  element  of  ugliness,  and  as  such  must 
lose  all  possibility  of  becoming  an  element  in  the  beautiful. 

One  further  word,  in  closing,  upon  the  closely  allied  question  as 
to  the  nature  of  worth- values.  There  is  a  worth-value  involved 
in  the  Good,  and  a  worth-value  involved  in  the  True,  and  a  worth- 


THE  RELATIONS   OF  ESTHETICS  433 

value  involved  in  the  Beautiful:  and  each  of  these  worth-values 
in  itself  seems  to  be  involved  with  pleasure-getting.  Now  if  this  is 
the  case,  then,  under  the  theory  I  uphold,  any  worth-value  should  be 
a  possible  aesthetic  element,  and  this  I  think  it  will  be  granted  is 
true.  But  the  distinctions  between  these  worth-values  are  on  differ- 
ent planes,  as  it  were.  In  the  case  of  the  worth-value  of  the  Good, 
we  appreciate  the  worth-pleasure  within  the  realm  of  the  Real  of 
Expression,  that  is,  of  impulse.  In  the  case  of  the  worth-value  of  the 
True  (in  the  narrow  sense) ,  we  appreciate  the  worth-pleasure  within 
the  realm  of  the  Real  in  other  fields  than  that  of  expression  or  that 
of  impression.  In  the  case  of  the  worth-value  of  the  Beautiful,  we 
appreciate  the  worth-pleasure  within  the  realm  of  the  Real  of  Im- 
pression; that  is,  we  appreciate,  with  pleasure,  the  significance  for 
life  of  the  existence  of  relatively  permanent  pleasure  in  and  for 
itself. 


THE    FUNDAMENTAL    QUESTIONS    OF    CONTEMPORARY 

AESTHETICS 

BY    MAX   DESSOIR 
{Translated  from  the  German  by  Miss  Ethel  D.  Puffer,  Cambridge,  Mass.) 

[Max  Dessoir,  Professor  of  Philosophy,  University  of  Berlin,  since  1897.  b. 
1867,  Berlin,  Germany.  Ph.D.  Berlin,  1889;  M.D.  Wtirzburg,  1892.  Pri- 
vat-docent,  University  of  Berlin,  1892-97.  Member  German  Psychological 
Society,  Society  for  Psychical  Research,  London.  Author  of  The  Double  Ego; 
History  of  the  New  German  Psychology  ;  Philosophical  Reader;  Msihetik  u.All- 
gemeine  Kunstwissenschaft ;  and  many  other  works  and  papers  an  philosophy.] 


In  the  development  which  our  science  has  undergone,  from  its 
inception  up  to  the  present  day,  one  thought  has  held  a  central 
place,  —  that  aesthetic  enjoyment  and  production,  beauty  and  art, 
are  inseparably  allied.  The  subject-matter  of  this  science  is  held  to 
be,  though  varied,  of  a  unitary  character.  Art  is  considered  as  the 
representation  of  the  beautiful,  which  comes  to  pass  out  of  an  ses- 
thetic  state  or  condition,  and  is  experienced  in  a  similar  attitude;  the 
science  which  deals  with  these  two  psychical  states,  with  the  beau- 
tiful and  its  modifications,  and  with  art  in  its  varieties,  is,  inasmuch 
as  it  constitutes  a  unity,  designated  by  the  single  name  of  aesthetics. 

The  critical  thought  of  the  present  day  is,  however,  beginning  to 
question  whether  the  beautiful,  the  aesthetic,  and  art  stand  to  one 
another  in  a  relation  that  can  be  termed  almost  an  identity.  The 
undivided  sway  of  the  beautiful  has  already  been  assailed.  Since 
art  includes  the  tragic  and  the  comic,  the  graceful  and  the  sublime, 
and  even  the  ugly,  and  since  aesthetic  pleasure  can  attach  itself  to 
all  these  categories,  it  is  clear  that  by  "the  beautiful"  something 
narrower  must  be  meant  than  the  artistically  and  aesthetically 
valuable.  Yet  beauty  might  still  constitute  the  end  and  aim  and 
central  point  of  art,  and  it  might  be  that  the  other  categories  but 
denote  the  way  to  beauty  —  beauty  in  a  state  of  becoming,  as  it 
were. 

But  even  this  view,  which  sees  in  beauty  the  real  content  of  art, 
and  the  central  object  of  aesthetic  experiences,  is  open  to  serious 
question.  It  is  confronted  with  the  fact,  above  all,  that  the  beauty 
enjoyed  in  life  and  that  enjoyed  in  art  are  not  the  same.  The  artist's 
copy  of  the  beauty  of  nature  takes  on  a  quite  new  character.  Solid 
objects  in  space  become  in  painting  flat  pictures,  the  existent  is  in 
poetry  transformed  into  matter  of  speech;  and  in  every  realm  is  a 


THE  FUNDAMENTAL   QUESTIONS   OF   ESTHETICS    435 

like  metamorphosis.  The  subjective  impression  might  indeed  be  sup- 
posed to  remain  the  same,  in  spite  of  objective  differentiations.  But 
even  that  is  not  the  case.  Living  human  beauty  —  an  acknowledged 
passport  for  its  possessor  —  speaks  to  all  our  senses;  it  often  stirs 
sex-feeling  in  however  delicate  and  scarce  conscious  a  way;  it 
involuntarily  influences  our  actions.  On  the  other  hand,  there  hangs 
about  the  marble  statue  of  a  naked  human  being  an  atmosphere 
of  coolness  in  which  we  do  not  consider  whether  we  are  looking 
upon  man  or  woman:  even  the  most  beauteous  body  is  enjoyed  as 
sexless  shape,  like  the  beauty  of  a  landscape  or  a  melody.  To 
the  aesthetic  impression  of  the  forest  belongs  its  aromatic  fragrance, 
to  the  impression  of  tropical  vegetation  its  glowing  heat,  while 
from  the  enjoyment  of  art  the  sensations  of  the  lower  senses  are 
barred.  In  return  for  what  is  lost,  as  it  were,  art-enjoyment  involves 
pleasure  in  the  personality  of  the  artist,  and  in  his  power  to  over- 
come difficulties,  and  in  the  same  way  many  other  elements  of  pleas- 
ure, which  are  never  produced  by  natural  beauty.  Accordingly, 
what  we  call  beautiful  in  art  must  be  distinguished  from  what  goes 
by  that  name  in  life,  both  as  regards  the  object  and  the  subjective 
impression. 

Another  point,  too,  appears  from  our  examples.  Assuming  that 
we  may  call  the  pure,  pleasurable  contemplation  of  actual  things 
and  events  aesthetic,  —  and  what  reason  against  it  could  be  adduced 
from  common  usage  ?  —  it  is  thus  clear  that  the  circle  of  the  aesthetic 
is  wider  than  the  field  of  art.  Our  admiring  and  adoring  self-abandon- 
ment to  nature-beauties  bears  all  the  marks  of  the  aesthetic  attitude, 
and  needs  for  all  that  no  connection  with  art.  Further:  in  all  in- 
tellectual and  social  spheres  a  part  of  the  productive  energy  expresses 
itself  in  aesthetic  forms;  these  products,  which  are  not  works  of  art, 
are  yet  aesthetically  enjoyed.  As  numberless  facts  of  daily  experience 
show  us  that  taste  can  develop  and  become  effective  independently 
of  art,  we  must  then  concede  to  the  sphere  of  the  aesthetic  a  wider 
circumference  than  that  of  art. 

This  is  not  to  maintain  that  the  circle  of  art  is  a  narrow  section  of 
a  large  field.  On  the  contrary,  the  aesthetic  principle  does  not  by 
any  means  exhaust  the  content  and  purpose  of  that  realm  of  human 
production  which  taken  together  we  call  "art."  Every  true  work  of 
art  is  extraordinarily  complex  in  its  motives  and  its  effects;  it  arises 
not  alone  from  the  free  play  of  aesthetic  impulse,  and  aims  at  more 
than  pure  beauty  —  at  more  than  aesthetic  pleasure.  The  desires 
and  energies  in  which  art  is  grounded  are  in  no  way  fulfilled  by 
the  serene  satisfaction  which  is  the  traditional  criterion  of  the  aes- 
thetic impression,  as  of  the  aesthetic  object.  In  reality  the  arts 
have  a  function  in  intellectual  and  social  life,  through  which  they  are 
closely  bound  up  with  all  our  knowing  and  willing. 


436  ESTHETICS 

It  is,  therefore,  the  duty  of  a  general  science  of  art  to  take  account 
of  the  broad  facts  of  art  in  all  its  relations.  Esthetics  is  not  capable 
of  this  task,  if  it  is  to  have  a  determined,  self-complete,  and  clearly 
bounded  content.  We  may  no  longer  obliterate  the  differences 
between  the  two  disciplines,  but  must  rather  so  sharply  separate 
them  by  ever  finer  distinctions  that  the  really  existent  connections 
become  clear.  The  first  step  thereto  has  been  taken  by  Hugo  Spitzer. 
The  relation  of  earlier  to  current  views  is  comparable  to  that  between 
materialism  and  positivism.  While  materialism  ventured  on  a  pretty 
crude  resolution  of  the  spiritual  into  the  corporeal,  positivism  set 
up  a  hierarchy  of  forces  of  nature,  whose  order  was  determined 
by  the  relation  of  dependence.  Thus  mechanical  forces,  physico- 
chemical  processes,  the  biological  and  the  social-historical  groups 
of  facts,  are  not  traced  back  each  to  the  preceding  by  an  inner  con- 
nection, but  are  so  linked  that  the  higher  orders  appear  as  dependent 
on  the  lower.  In  the  same  way  is  it  now  sought  to  link  art  methodo- 
logically with  the  aesthetic.  Perhaps  even  more  closely,  indeed,  since 
already  aesthetics  and  the  science  of  art  often  play  into  each  other's 
hands.,  like  the  tunnel-workers  who  pierce  a  mountain  from  opposite 
points,  to  meet  at  its  centre. 

Often  it  so  happens,  but  not  invariably.  In  many  cases  research  is 
carried  to  an  end,  quite  irrespectively  of  what  is  going  on  in  other 
quarters.  The  field  is  too  great,  and  the  interests  are  too  various. 
Artists  recount  their  experiences  in  the  process  of  creation,  con- 
noisseurs enlighten  us  as  to  the  technique  of  the  special  arts;  socio- 
logists investigate  the  social  function,  ethnologists  the  origin,  of  art; 
psychologists  explore  the  aesthetic  impression,  partly  by  experiment, 
partly  through  conceptual  analysis;  philosophers  expound  aesthetic 
methods  and  principles;  the  historians  of  literature,  music,  and 
pictorial  art  have  collected  a  vast  deal  of  material  —  and'  the  sum 
total  of  these  scientific  inquiries  constitutes  the  most  substantial 
though  not  the  greatest  part  of  the  published  discussions,  which, 
written  from  every  possible  point  of  view,  abound  in  newspapers  and 
magazines.  "  There  is  left,  then,  for  the  serious  student,  naught  but 
to  resolve  to  fix  a  central  point  somewhere,  and  thence  to  find  out 
a  way  to  deal  with  all  the  rest  as  outlying  territory  "  (Goethe). 

Only  by  the  mutual  setting  of  bounds  can  a  united  effect  be  pos- 
sible from  the  busy  whirl  of  efforts.  Contradictory  and  heterogeneous 
facts  are  still  very  numerous.  He  who  should  undertake  to  construct 
thereof  a  clear  intelligible  unity  of  concepts,  would  destroy  the 
energy  which  now  proves  itself  in  the  encounters,  crossing  of  swords, 
and  lively  controversies  of  scholars,  and  would  mutilate  the  fullness 
of  experience  which  now  expresses  itself  in  the  manifold  special 
researches.  System  and  method  signify  for  us:  to  be  free  from  one 
system  and  one  method. 


THE  FUNDAMENTAL   QUESTIONS   OF   ESTHETICS    437 

II 

If  we  are  to  consider  how  we  answer  to-day  the  questions  put  for 
scientific  consideration  as  to  the  facts  of  aesthetic  life  and  of  art,  first 
of  all  we  must  examine  the  now  prevailing  theories  of  aesthetics. 
They  fall  in  general  into  sesthetic  objectivism  and  subjectivism. 
By  the  first  collective  name  we  denote  the  aggregate  of  all  theories 
which  find  the  characteristic  of  their  field  of  inquiry  essentially  in 
the  quality  and  conformation  of  the  object,  not  in  the  attitude  of 
the  enjoying  subject.  This  quality  of  the  aesthetically  valuable  is 
most  easily  characterized  by  setting  it  off  against  reality.  Of  such 
theories,  which  explain  "the  beautiful"  and  art  from  their  relation 
to  what  is  given  in  nature,  naturalism  stands  for  the  identity  of  real- 
ity and  art,  while  the  various  types  of  idealism  set  forth  art  as  more 
than  reality,  and  vice  versa,  formalism,  illusionism,  sensualism  make 
it  less  than  reality. 

Inasmuch  as  naturalism  is  still  defended  only  by  a  handful  of 
artists  who  write,  it  would  appear  almost  superfluous  to  consider  it. 
But  the  refutations  of  it  which  are  still  appearing  indicate  that  it 
must  have  some  life.  And  in  fact  it  still  exists,  partly  as  a  present- 
day  phenomenon  in  literature  and  art,  partly  as  the  permanent 
conviction  of  many  artists.  The  naturalistic  style  testifies  to  revolt 
against  forms  and  notions  which  are  dying  out;  it  therefore  only 
attains  a  pure  aesthetic  interest  through  the  theoretic  ground  which 
is  furnished  to  it.  And  this  rests  above  all  on  the  testimony  of  the 
artists,  who  are  never  weary  of  assuring  us  that  they  immediately 
reproduce  what  is  given  in  perception.  Some  philosophical  concep- 
tions also  play  therein  a  certain  role.  The  adherents  of  the  doctrine 
that  only  the  sense-world  is  real  come  as  a  matter  of  course  to  the 
demand  that  art  shall  hold  itself  strictly  to  the  given.  And  what 
optimist,  who  explains  the  real  world  as  the  best  of  all  possible 
worlds,  can,  without  a  logical  weakening,  admit  a  play  of  imagination 
different  from  the  reality. 

-(Esthetic  idealism,  too,  is  borne  on  general  philosophical  premises. 
However  various  these  are,  in  this  they  all  agree,  that  the  world  is 
not  exhausted  by  appearances,  but  has  an  ideal  content  and  import, 
which  finds  in  the  aesthetic  and  in  the  field  of  art  its  expression  to 
sense.  Even  H.  Taine  sets  to  art  the  task  of  showing  the  "  dominant 
character"  of  things.  The  beautiful  is  therefore  something  higher 
than  the  chance  reality,  —  the  typical  as  over  against  the  anomalous 
natural  objects  or  events.  It  can  then  be  objectively  determined 
with  reference  to  its  typical  and  generic  quality  and  in  its  various 
kinds. 

Somewhat  different  is  the  case  of  formalism,  which  to-day  scarcely 
anywhere  sets  up  to  be  a  complete  system  of  aesthetics,  but  points 


438  ESTHETICS 

the  way  for  many  special  investigations.  It  seeks  the  sesthetically 
effective  in  the  form,  that  is,  in  the  relation  of  parts,  which  has 
in  principle  nothing  to  do  with  the  content  of  the  object.  Every 
clearly  perceptible  unity  in  manifoldness  is  pleasing.  As  this  ar- 
rangement is  independent  of  the  material,  the  aesthetic  represents 
only  a  part  of  reality. 

In  contrast  thereto,  illusionism  sets  the  world  of  art  as  a  whole  over 
against  the  whole  of  reality.  Art,  we  are  taught,  presents  neither  a 
new  aspect  of  the  given  nor  hidden  truth,  nor  piire  form;  it  is,  on  the 
contrary,  a  world  of  appearance  only,  and  is  to  be  enjoyed  without 
regard  to  connections  in  life  or  any  consequences.  While  we  other- 
wise consider  objects  as  to  how  they  serve  our  interests  and  as  to  their 
place  in  the  actual  connection  of  all  things,  in  the  esthetic  experi- 
ence this  twofold  relation  is  disregarded.  Neither  what  things  do 
for  us,  nor  what  they  do  for  each  other,  comes  in  question.  Their 
reality  disappears,  and  the  beautiful  semblance  comes  to  its  own. 
Konrad  Lange  has  given  to  this  theory  —  especially  in  the  line  of 
a  subjective  side,  to  be  later  mentioned  —  its  modern  form. 

Of  the  nearly-related  sensualism,  the  connoisseur  Fiedler  and  the 
sculptor  Hildebrand  are  the  recent  exponents;  Rutgers  Marshall 
and  certain  French  scholars  also  lean  that  way.  It  is  the  arts  which 
fix  the  transitory  element  of  the  sense-image,  hold  fast  the  fleeting, 
make  immortal  the  perishable,  and  lend  stability  and  permanence 
to  all  pleasure  that  is  bound  up  with  perception.  What  does  painting 
accomplish?  Arisen,  as  it  has,  out  of  the  demands  of  the  eye,  its 
sole  task  is  to  gain  for  the  undefined  form-  and  color-impressions 
of  reality  a  complete  and  stable  existence.  The  same  thing  is  true 
of  the  other  arts,  for  their  respective  sense-impressions. 

To  sum  up:  If  the  transformation  of  reality  is  acknowledged  as 
a  fundamental  principle  of  art,  it  is  also  to  be  granted  that  this  takes 
place  in  two  directions :  —  art  is  something  at  once  more  and  less 
than  nature.  Inasmuch  as  art  pushes  on  to  the  vraie  verite,  and  at 
the  same  time  disregards  all  that  is  not  of  the  nature  of  semblance 
or  image,  we  take  from  it  ideas  whose  quality  enthralls  and  stimu- 
lates us  quite  independently  of  their  meaning.  Art  shows  us  the 
hidden  essence  of  the  world  and  of  life  and  at  the  same  time  the 
outsides  of  things  created  for  our  pleasure;  that  is,  the  objects' 
pure  psychical  value  in  the  field  of  sense.  It  involves  a  lifting  above 
nature,  and  at  the  same  time  the  rounding  out  and  fulfillment  of 
sense.  Through  making  of  the  object  an  image,  it  frees  us  from  our 
surrounding,  yet  leaves  us  at  rest  in  it. 

We  turn  now  to  sesthetic  subjectivism.  Under  this  name  we  com- 
prehend the  essence  of  those  theories  which  seek  to  solve  the  riddle 
of  the  beautiful  by  a  general  characterization  of  the  sesthetic  atti- 
tude. Many  of  these  are  near  akin  to  the  objectivistic  theories;  some, 


THE  FUNDAMENTAL   QUESTIONS   OF   ESTHETICS     439 

however,  like  the  Einfiihlung-theoTy,  take  an  independent  place. 
For  the  former,  therefore,  a  mere  indication  will  suffice.  The  prin- 
ciple of  "semblance"  or  illusion,  for  instance,  takes  very  easily  a 
subjectivistic  turn.  The  question  then  runs:  Wherein  consists  the 
peculiarity  of  the  conscious  processes  which  are  set  up  by  the 
semblance?  The  answer  as  given  by  Meinong  and  Witasek  starts 
from  the  fact  that  the  totality  of  psychical  processes  falls  into  two 
divisions.  Every  process  in  one  division  has  its  counterpart  in  the 
other.  To  perception  corresponds  imagination,  to  judgment  assump- 
tion, to  real  emotion  ideal  emotion,  to  earnest  desire  fancied  desire. 
The  sesthetic  emotions  attached  to  assumptions,  the  semblance-emo- 
tions, that  is,  are  held  to  be  scarcely  distinguished,  so  far  as  feeling 
goes,  from  other  emotions,  at  most,  perhaps,  by  less  intensity.  The 
chief  difference  lies  rather  in  the  premise  or  basis  of  emotion;  and 
this  is  but  a  mere  assumption  or  fiction. 

A  critical  treatment  of  the  foregoing  cannot  be  given  here;  nor 
of  that  view  which  explains  the  psychical  condition  in  receiving  an 
sesthetic  impression  as  a  conscious  self-deception,  a  continued  and 
intentional  confusion  of  reality  and  semblance.  The  sesthetic  pleas- 
ure, according  to  this,  is  a  free  and  conscious  hovering  between 
reality  and  unreality;  or,  otherwise  expressed,  the  never  successful 
seeking  for  fusion  of  original  and  copy.  The  enjoyment  of  a  good 
graphic  representation  of  a  globe  would  then  depend  on  the  specta- 
tor's now  thinking  he  sees  a  real  globe,  now  being  sure  he  views  a  flat 
drawing. 

While  this  theory  has  found  but  small  acceptance,  comparatively 
many  modern  sestheticians  admit  the  doctrine  of  Einfithlung.  Its 
leading  exponent,  Theodor  Lipps,  sees  the  decisive  characteristic 
of  sesthetic  enjoyment  in  the  fusion  of  an  alien  experience  with  one's 
own:  as  soon  as  something  objectively  given  furnishes  us  the  pos- 
sibility of  freely  living  ourselves  into  it,  we  feel  sesthetic  pleasure. 
In  the  example  of  the  Doric  column,  rearing  itself  and  gathering 
itself  up  to  our  view,  Lipps  has  sought  to  show  how  given  space- 
forms  are  interpreted  first  dynamically,  then  anthropomorphically. 
We  read  into  the  geometrical  figure  not  only  the  expression  of  energy, 
but  also  free  purposiveness.  In  so  far  as  we  look  at  it  in  the  light  of 
our  own  activity,  and  sympathize  with  it  accordingly,  in  so  far  do 
we  feel  it  as  beautiful. 

Could  we  enter  upon  a  critical  discussion  at  this  point,  it  would 
appear  that  the  Einfuhlung-iheory,  like  its  fellows,  is  open  to  well- 
founded  objections.  The  belief  in  an  all-explaining  formula  is  a 
delusion.  In  truth,  every  one  of  the  enumerated  principles  is  rela- 
tively justified.  And  as  they  all  have  points  of  similarity  with  one 
another,  it  is  not  hard  for  the  past-master  of  terminology  and  the 
technique  of  concepts  to  epitomize  the  common  element  in  a  single 


440  AESTHETICS 

phrase  or  thesis.  Still,  nothing  is  gained  by  such  a  general  formula 
in  presence  of  the  richness  of  the  reality;  and  just  as  little  —  as  an 
exhaustive  treatment  would  have  to  prove  —  by  the  concise  ex- 
position of  a  single  method  for  our  science. 

The  specially  approved  method  of  procedure  at  the  present  day 
is  that  of  psychological  description  and  explanation.  It  seems, 
indeed,  very  natural  to  see  in  psychical  processes  the  real  subject- 
matter  of  Eesthetics,  and  in  psychology,  accordingly,  the  science  to 
which  it  is  subordinate.  Some  philosophers,  however,  —  among 
whom  I  may  instance  Jonas  Cohn,  —  wish  to  make  of  aesthetics  a 
science  of  values,  and  demand  that  on  the  basis  of  this  pretension 
the  mutually  contradictory  judgments  of  taste  and  types  of  art  be 
tried  and  tested.  They  will  have  no  mere  descriptive  and  explan- 
atory eesthetics,  but  a  normative,  precept-giving  science.  In  truth, 
the  opposition  of  the  schools  is  complete  at  every  point;  in  the 
writings  of  Volkelt  and  Groos  we  have  the  proof  of  it. 

Ill 

The  special  research  in  the  narrower  field  of  aesthetics  is  at  present 
almost  entirely  of  the  psychological  type.  Our  survey  can  touch 
upon  only  the  salient  points. 

The  aim  of  the  extended  and  highly  detailed  study  consists  in 
fixating  by  means  of  psychological  analysis  the  course  of  develop- 
ment, the  effective  elements,  and  the  various  sub-species  of  the 
aesthetic  experience.  Certain  philosophers  seek  a  point  of  departure 
for  this  undertaking  in  the  aesthetic  object.  Thus  Volkelt 's  system 
of  aesthetics  finds,  for  the  chief  elements  of  the  aesthetic  enjoyment, 
corresponding  features  in  the  object;  in  the  special  field  of  poetry 
Dilthey  has  undertaken 'an  analysis  along  the  same  lines.  For  the 
most  part,  however,  such  dissection  is  limited  to  the  subjective  side. 
In  Wundt's  psychology,  for  instance,  the  aesthetic  state  of  mind  is 
shown  to  be  built  up  of  sense-feelings,  feelings  from  perceptions,  in- 
tellectual and  emotional  excitements;  the  most  important,  that  is 
to  say,  the  pivotal  feelings,  which  are  bound  up  with  space-  and 
time-relations,  become  in  turn  the  condition  and  support  of  the 
higher  emotions,  because  they  lead  over  from  the  field  of  sense  to 
that  of  the  logical  and  emotional. 

If  we  limit  ourselves  to  the  psychological,  we  must  first  ask  in  what 
order  the  elements  of  the  aesthetic  impression  are  wont  to  follow 
each  other.  The  phases  of  this  development,  however,  are  as  yet  not 
completely  studied,  although  they  are  of  great  significance  for  the 
differences  in  enjoyment.  The  second  problem  concerns  the  con- 
stitution (taken  as  timeless)  of  the  experience.  All  formulas  which 
attempt  to  fix  in  two  words  the  totality  of  the  impression  fail  com- 


THE  FUNDAMENTAL   QUESTIONS   OF   ESTHETICS     441 

pletely,  —  so  extraordinarily  various  and  manifold  are  the  factors 
which  enter  here.  What  these  are  and  how  they  are  bound  together 
is  the  question  which  is  for  the  moment  occupying  the  scholars  with 
a  leaning  toward  psychology. 

The  aesthetic  impression  is  an  emotion.  According  to  the  well- 
known  sensualistic  theory  of  the  emotions,  it  must  therefore,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  more  than  mere  perception  or  idea,  be  composed  of  organic 
sensations.  G.  Sergi  and  Karl  Lange  see,  in  fact,  the  peculiar  mark 
of  the  aesthetic  experience  in  the  general  sensations  which  appear 
with  changes  in  the  circulation,  breathing,  etc.  Unprejudiced  ob- 
servation must  satisfy  every  one  that  much  in  all  this  is  true.  On  the 
other  hand,  it  is  to  be  recalled  that  we  do  not  reckon  the  organic 
sensations  to  the  objective  qualities  of  aesthetic  things,  and  that  we 
cannot  explain  in  this  way  every  artistic  enjoyment.  —  In  regard  to 
the  sensations  of  taste,  smell,  and  touch,  it  is  generally  granted  that 
they  play  a  certain  role,  even  if  but  as  reproduced  ideas  and  only 
corresponding  to  natural  beauty.  Among  the  most  important  are 
the  attitudes  and  imitative  movements,  finely  investigated  by  Karl 
Gtoos.  —  To  this  must  be  added  the  sensuous  pleasantness  of  visual 
and  auditory  perceptions.  Yet  attempts  to  construct  the  aesthetic 
enjoyment  in  its  entirety  out  of  such  pleasure-factors  have  so  far 
failed.  The  undertaking  is  already  wrecked  by  the  fact  that  elements 
displeasing  to  sense  are  demonstrably  present,  not  only  as  negligible 
admixtures,  but  also  as  necessary  factors.  The  relations  of  similarity 
between  the  contents  of  a  sense-field,  and  the  spatial  and  temporal 
connections  between  them,  are  in  any  case  incomparably  more 
important;  we  devote  to  them,  therefore,  a  closer  consideration. 
Finally,  alongside  all  these  ideas  and  the  emotions  immediately 
attaching  to  them,  there  must  be  arrayed  the  great  multitude  of  as- 
sociated ideas  and  connecting  judgments.  While  scientific  interest 
in  the  associations  is  now  greatly  diminished,  explanations  of  the 
part  played  by  the  element  of  really  active  thought  are  many.  A 
universally  satisfactory  theory  is  still  to  appear,  for  the  reason, 
above  all,  that  here  the  higher  principles  referred  to  in  the  second 
section  enter  into  the  problems. 

Elementary  aesthetics,  therefore,  willingly  turns  aside  from  the 
shore  of  the  very  complex  emotions,  of  association,  Einfiihlung  and 
illusion  in  aesthetic  experience,  in  order  to  become  independent  of 
general  philosophical  fundamental  conceptions.  Its  own  field  lies 
in  the  general  province  of  the  perception-feelings  determined  im- 
mediately by  the  object:  more  exactly,  of  the  feelings  which  are 
induced  partly  by  the  relations  of  similarity,  partly  by  the  outer 
connections  of  the  content,  partly  by  the  linking  of  inner  and  outer 
reference.  The  qualitative  relation  of  tones  and  colors  arouses  the 
so-called  feelings  of  harmony;    the  arrangement  in  space  and  time 


442  ESTHETICS  . 

awakes  the  so-called  proportion-f eelings ;  and  from  the  cooperation 
of  these  two  arise  the  so-called  aesthetic  complication-feelings. 

As  to  the  pleasurable  tone-  and  color-combinations,  the  first  are 
better  known  than  the  second,  but  even  their  theoretical  interpre- 
tation is  not  well  settled.  More  diligent  and  successful  at  the  present 
time  is  the  research  into  the  proportion-feelings.  So  far  as  these 
bear  upon  space-relations,  they  attach  either  to  the  outlines  or  to  the 
structure  of  the  forms.  The  bounding-lines  are  then  pleasing,  one 
theory  holds,  when  they  correspond  to  the  easiest  eye-movements,  and 
in  general  meet  our  desire  for  easy,  effortless  orientation.  Another 
doctrine,  already  referred  to,  explains  their  aesthetic  value  from  a 
co5peration  of  general  bodily  feelings,  especially  sensations  of 
breathing  and  equilibrium.  Accurate  experiments  have  not  succeeded 
in  finding  a  real  conformity  to  law  in  either  the  first  or  the  second 
direction.  In  the  matter  of  the  structure  of  forms,  symmetry  in 
the  horizontal  position,  and  the  proportion  of  the  golden  section 
in  the  vertical  position,  receive  especial  attention.  All  those  space- 
shapes  may  be  called  symmetrical,  whose  halves  are  of  equal  value 
{Esthetically.  How  these  must  be  constituted,  has  been  studied 
from  the  simplest  examples  by  Miinsterberg  and  his  pupils.  The 
explanation  of  the  pleasing  quality  rests  on  the  fact  that  the  spec- 
tator feels  the  contents  of  the  two  halves  —  lines  or  colors  —  as  light 
or  heavy,  according  to  the  energy  expended  in,  the  necessary  eye- 
movements.  In  the  vertical  position  a  proportion  pleases  (as  does  also 
equality)  which  is  only  approximately  that  of  the  golden  section. 
The  numerical  proportion  is,  therefore,  not  the  ground  of  pleasure, 
for  otherwise  those  forms  which  are  thus  divided  would  have  to  be 
the  absolutely  beautiful  ones,  and  the  more  a  division  varies  from 
the  exact  fraction,  the  more  would  it  sacrifice  in  beauty.  The  ground 
of  pleasure  is  rather  descried  in  the  fact  that  in  the  case  of  the  pleas- 
ing divisions  the  two  parts  stand  out  as  distinct  and  clearly  character- 
ized, while  yet  unified  effect  is  secured  through  the  larger  division. 

The  temporal  ordering  of  an  aesthetic  character  is  that  of  rhythm. 
Concerning  the  aesthetic  object  as  such  —  that  is,  concerning  the 
metrical  forms  in  music  and  poetry,  the  views  are  still  widely  at 
variance;  this  is  true  to  a  startling  degree  of  poetr}^,  because  here 
the  element,  that  is  to  say,  the  word,  is  made  up  of  accented  and 
unaccented  syllables,  and  because  the  tendency  of  the  logical  con- 
nections of  the  content  to  create  unities  cannot  be  done  away  with. 
This  state  of  confusion  is  so  much  the  more  to  be  regretted  as  it  is 
just  to  the  art-forms  that  the  most  vivid  rhythmical  feelings  attach. 
The  psychological  investigations  of  Neumann,  Bolton,  and  others  have 
nevertheless  much  advanced  our  scientific  understanding  of  this 
subject.  A  new  point  of  view  has  taken  its  rise  from  Souriau  and 
Bilcher:    the  connection  of  the  art-rhythm  with  work  and  other 


THE  FUNDAMENTAL   QUESTIONS   OF   ESTHETICS     443 

aspects  of  life.  But  the  collections  of  data  do  not  yet  render  it  pos- 
sible to  settle  the  question  in  what  manner  the  rhythm  of  work, 
which  runs  on  automatically,  and  is  controlled  by  the  idea  of  an  end, 
goes  over  into  aesthetic  rhythm. 

The  aesthetic  complication-feelings  are  bound  up  Tvith  the  products 
of  the  fusion  of  rhythm  and  harmony,  form  and  color,  rhythm  and 
form  (in  the  dance).  So  long  as  all  elements  of  association  are 
neglected,  three  characteristics  remain  to  be  noted:  an  increasing 
valuation  of  the  absolute  quantity,  the  building-up  of  definite 
form-qualities  (Gestaltqualitdten) ,  and  a  reconciliation  or  harmony 
of  differences,  wherein  the  quantitative  element  is  wont  to  be  the 
unifying,  the  qualitative  element  the  separating  factor.  I  need  not, 
however,  go  any  further  into  investigations  so  subtle,  and  even  now 
merely  in  their  beginnings. 

This  entire  fabric  of  experience,  from  M'hich  but  a  few  threads 
have  been  drawn  out  to  view,  can  now  take  on  various  shadings. 
These  we  refer  to  as  the  aesthetic  moods,  or  by  a  less  psychological 
name,  as  the  aesthetic  categories.  The  ideally  beautiful  and  the 
sublime,  the  tragic  and  the  ugly,  the  comic  and  the  graceful,  are 
the  best  known  among  them.  Modern  science  has  shown  most 
interest  in  the  study  of  the  comic  and  the  tragic.  According  to  Lipps 
the  specific  emotion  of  the  comic  arises  in  the  disappointing  of  a 
psychical  preparation  for  a  strong  impression,  by  the  appearance  of 
a  weak  one.  The  pleasurable  character  of  the  experience  would  be 
explained  by  the  fact  that  the  surplus  of  psychical  impulse,  like  every 
excess  of  inner  energy,  is  felt  as  agreeable.  The  tragic  mood  is  under- 
stood no  longer  as  arising  in  fear  and  pity,  but  in  pathos  and  wonder. 
Its  objective  correlate  should  not  be  forced  to  the  standard  of  a  nar- 
row ethics.  The  demand  for  guilt  and  expiation  is  being  given  up 
by  progressive  thinkers  in  aesthetics;  but  the  constituents  of  tragedy 
remain  fast  bound  to  the  realm  of  harshness,  cruelty,  and  dissonance. 

IV 

From  a  period  more  or  less  remote  there  have  existed  poetics, 
musical  theory,  and  the  science  of  art.  To  examine  the  presupposi- 
tions methods  and  aims  of  these  disciplines  from  the  epistemological 
point  of  view,  and  to  sum  up  and  compare  their  most  important  results , 
is  the  task  of  a  general  science  of  art;  this  has  besides,  in  the  pro- 
blems of  artistic  creation  and  the  origin  of  art,  and  of  the  classification 
of  the  arts  and  their  social  function,  certain  fields  of  inquiry  that 
would  otherT\ase  have  no  definite  place.  They  are  worked,  indeed, 
with  remarkable  diligence  and  productiveness.  Most  to  be  regretted, 
on  the  other  hand,  is  that  so  little  energy  is  applied  to  laying  the 
epistemological  foundation. 

The  theory  of  the  development  of    art  deals  with  it  both  in  its 


444  ESTHETICS 

individual  and  its  generally  human  aspect.  Concerning  the  genesis  of 
the  child's  understanding  of  art  and  impulse  to  produce  it,  we  learn 
most  from  the  studies  of  his  drawings  at  an  early  age.  Here  are  to  be 
noted  well-established  results  of  observation,  even  though  as  yet 
they  are  few  in  number.  On  the  other  hand,  the  unfolding  of  primi- 
tive feeling  (and  of  the  aesthetic  sensibility  in  general)  during  the 
historical  period  can  be  only  approximately  reconstructed.  The 
case  is  somewhat  more  favorable  for  our  information  in  regard  to 
the  beginnings  of  art,  especially  since  it  has  been  systematically 
assembled  by  Ernst  Grosse  and  Yrjo  Hirn.  If  the  conditions  of  the 
most  primitive  of  the  races  now  living  in  a  state  of  nature  can  be 
taken  as  identical  with  those  at  the  beginnings  of  civilization,  the 
entire  vast  material  of  ethnology  can  be  made  use  of.  We  gather 
therefrom  how  close-linked  with  the  useful  and  the  necessary  beauty 
is,  and  see  clearly  that  primitive  art  is  thoroughly  penetrated  by 
the  purpose  of  a  common  enjoyment,  and  is  effective  in  a  social 
way;  but  beyond  such  general  principles  one  can  go  only  with 
hesitation,  inasmuch  as  it  seems  scarcely  possible  to  us,  creatures  of 
civilization,  to  fix  the  boundaries  of  what  is  really  art  there. 

There  are  three  conjectures  as  to  objective  origin  of  art.  It  may 
be  that  the  separate  arts  have  developed  through  variation  from  one 
embryonic  state.  Or  the  main  arts  may  have  been  separate  from  the 
very  first,  having  arisen  independently  of  each  other.  Finally,  there 
are  middle  views,  like  that  of  Spencer,  according  to  which  poetry, 
music,  and  the  dance  on  the  one  hand,  and  writing,  painting,  and 
sculpture  on  the  other,  have  a  common  root ;  Mobius  recognizes 
three  primitive  arts,  to  which  the  others  are  to  be  traced  back.  The 
solution  of  this  question  would  be  especially  important,  could  one 
hope  to  find  Darwin's  maxim  for  all  setiological  investigations  valid 
for  our  field  also  —  that  is,  the  dictum:  What  is  of  like  origin  is  of 
like  character. 

As  psychological  conditions,  from  which  the  artistic  activity  is 
likely  first  to  have  arisen,  the  following  functions  have  been  suggested 
and  maintained,  — the  plajMnstinet,  imitation,  the  need  for  expres- 
sion and  communication,  the  sense  for  order  and  arrangement,  the 
impulse  to  attract  others  and  the  opposed  impulse  to  startle  others. 
Each  of  these  theories  of  conditions  must  clearly  connect  itself  with 
one  or  the  other  of  the  just-named  three  theories  of  art's  origin;  for 
had  music,  taken  in  our  sense  and  independently,  existed  as  the  orig- 
inal art,  one  could  hardly  regard  imitation  as  the  psychological  root 
of  art.  All  in  all,  art  and  the  play-instinct  seem  most  closely  linked; 
that  is  also  true,  moreover,  of  its  development  with  the  child. 

I  come  now  to  the  fundamental  problems  of  artistic  creation.  It 
is  they  which  present  the  most  obstinate  difficulties  to  a  thorough 
and  exact  investigation,  for  experiment  and  the  questionnaire  — 


THE  FUNDAMENTAL  QUESTIONS   OF   AESTHETICS     445 

which  aims  at  least  at  objectivity  —  are  but  crude  means  to  the  end  in 
view.  At  the  present  day,  as  eariier,  there  is  no  lack  of  very  refined, 
penetrating,  —  nay,  brilliant  analyses.  They  have  a  very  superior 
value;  but  this  has  no  special  significance  for  the  present  status  of 
the  science  of  aesthetics,  and  for  this  reason  our  survey  may  omit 
much  which  yet  has  an  interest  for  individuals. 

The  influence  of  heredity  and  environment  on  the  artist's  talent 
offers  rich  material  for  research.  It  is  conceded,  though,  that  how 
the  most  material  and  the  most  spiritual  of  influences,  inherited 
disposition  and  fortune,  the  chances  of  descent  and  of  intercourse 
with  one's  fellows, — how  all  this  is  fused  into  a  unified  personality, 
can  be  established  only  in  individual  cases  by  the  biographer.  A 
second  very  productive  source  of  material  in  this  field  has  appeared 
in  Lombroso's  teaching.  The  days  of  the  most  violent  controversies 
lie  behind  us.  It  is  the  general  view  that  genius  and  madness  are  near 
allied  in  their  expression,  that  greatness  often  breaks  forth  in  ques- 
tionable forms;  yet  the  majority  perceive  an  essential  difference  ;  the 
genius  points  onward,  the  mind  diseased  harks  back;  the  one  has 
purposive  significance,  the  other  not.  After  these  more  introductory 
inquiries,  the  real  work  begins.  It  has  to  show  in  what  points  every 
gift  for  art  coincides  with  generally  disseminated  abilities,  and  just 
where  the  specific  power  sets  in,  which  the  inartistic  person  lacks. 
Take,  for  example,  the  memory.  We  retain  this  or  that  fact  without, 
in  principle,  any  selection;  the  remembrance  of  the  artist,  on  the 
contrary,  is  dissociative  —  it  favors  what  is  needful  for  its  own  ends. 
The  memory  of  the  painter  battens  on  forms  and  colors,  the  conscious- 
ness of  the  musician  is  filled  with  melodies,  the  fancy  of  the  poet  lives 
in  verbal  images.  Also  there  is,  especially  with  the  poet,  a  peculiar 
understanding  for  human  experience.  In  truth,  the  fanciful  products 
of  the  imagination  are  but  the  starting-point  for  the  soul-know- 
ledge of  the  poet.  Without  going  into  details  we  may  say  that  by 
such  penetrating  and  delimiting  analyses  the  superficial  theory  of 
inspiration  is  refuted.  Out  of  date,  too,  is  the  notion  that  the  artist 
creates  by  putting  things  together;  on  the  contrary  his  fancy  has 
the  whole  before  the  parts,  it  gives  to  the  world  an  organism,  within 
which  the  members  gradually  emerge.  Finally,  the  old  theory  is  no 
longer  held,  according  to  which  the  work  of  art  is  already  complete 
in  the  inner  man,  and  afterwards  merely  brought  to  light.  More 
definite  explanation  is  given  by  the  doctrine  of  the  way  in  which  the 
artistic  creation  runs  its  course,  which  Eduard  v,  Hartmann  has 
skillfully  portrayed.    • 

The  distinction,  differentiation,  and  comparison  of  the  special 
arts  offers  opportunity  and  material  for  numberless  special  studies. 
Music  is  here  the  least  fully  represented,  since  it  is  only  exceptionally 
that  art-philosophers  feel  a  drawing  to  it.    So  much  the  more,  how- 


446  ESTHETICS 

ever,  are  they  inclined  to  the  study  of  poetry.  They  are  even  begin- 
ning to  make  use,  for  poetics,  of  the  studies  in  the  modern  psychology 
of  language,  since  it  is  acknowledged  that  language  is  the  essential 
element,  and  thus  more  than  the  mere  form  of  expression,  of  the 
poetic  art.  Th.  A.  Meyer  has  thrown  an  apple  of  discord  into  the 
question  whether  the  poet's  words  must,  in  order  to  arouse  pleasure, 
also  awake  an  image.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  the  aesthetic  value  does  not 
depend  on  the  chance-aroused  sense-images,  but  on  the  language 
itself  and  the  images  which  belong  to  it  alone;  for  the  most  part  the 
understanding  of  the  words  alone  is  enough  to  give  the  reader  pleas- 
ure in  the  poetic  treatment.  In  the  general  theory  of  the  visu- 
ally representative  arts  there  are  two  opposed  doctrines.  The  one 
emphasizes  the  common  element,  and  believes  to  have  found  it  in 
the  so-called  Fernhild,  or  distant  image;  the  other  seeks  salvation 
in  complete  separations  —  as,  for  instance,  of  the  so-called  Griff el- 
kunst,  or  graphic  art,  from  painting.  Only  the  future  can  decide 
between  them. 

The  existence  of  the  total  field  of  art  as  an  essential  factor  of  hu- 
man endeavors  involves  difficulties  which  must  be  removed  partly 
in  the  philosophical  consideration,  partly  in  law  and  governmental 
practice.  The  last  factor  must  also  be  taken  account  of  in  theory; 
for  so  long  as  we  do  not  live  in  an  ideal  world,  the  state  will  claim 
regulation  of  all  activities  expressing  themselves  in  it,  and  so  also 
Of  art.  In  first  line  it  is  concerned  for  art's  relation  to  morality. 
Secondly,  the  social  problems  arise:  does  art  bind  men  together, 
or  part  them?  does  it  reconcile  or  intensify  oppositions?  is  it  demo- 
cratic or  aristocratic?  is  it  a  necessity  or  a  luxury?  does  it  further  or 
reject  patriotic,  ethical,  pedagogical  ends?  The  artistic  education  of 
youth  and  the  race  has  become  a  burning  question.  Huskin  and 
Morris  have  developed  from  art-critics  to  critics  of  the  social  order, 
and  Tolstoi  has  contracted  the  democratic  point  of  view  to  the 
most  extreme  degree.  With  the  desire  to  transform  art  from  the 
privilege  of  the  few  to  the  possession  of  all  is,  finally,  bound  up  the 
wish  that  art  shall  emerge  from  another  seclusion  —  that  it  shall  not 
be  throned  in  museums  and  libraries,  in  theatres  and  concert-halls, 
but  shall  mingle  with  our  daily  domestic  life,  and  direct  and  color 
every  act  of  the  scholar  as  of  the  peasant. 

A  satisfactory  decision  can  be  reached  only  by  him  who  keeps  in 
view  that  art  presents  something  extremely  complex,  and  by  no 
means  mere  aesthetic  form;  that,  on  the  other  hand,  the  aesthetic 
life  is  not  banished  to  the  sacred  circle  of  the  independent  arts. 
With  this  conclusion  we  return  to  the  first  words  of  our  reflec- 
tions herein  presented. 


SPECIAL    BIBLIOGRAPHY    PREPARED    BY    PROFESSOR 
DESSOIR  FOR  HIS  ADDRESS 

Thaddeus  L.  Bolton,  Rhytlim.    Americ.  Joum.  of  Psychol.  1894.    vi,  145-238. 

Karl  Biicher,  Arbeit  und  Rhythmus.   3  Aufi.  Leipzig,  1902. 

Jonas  Cohn,  Allgemeine  ^sthetik,  Leipzig,  1901. 

Wilhelm  Dilthey,  Die  Einbildungshraft  des  Dichters.   Bausterne  zu  einer  Poetik. 

In  den  ZeUer  gewidmeten  Pliilos.  Aufsatzen,  Leipzig,  1887. 
Konrad  Fiedler,  Schriften  tiber  Kunst,  Leipzig,  1896. 
Karl  Groos,  Der  sesthetische  Genuss.   Giessen,  1902. 
Ernst  Grosse,  Die  Anfange  der  Kunst,  Freiburg  und  Leipzig,  1894. 
Eduard  von  Hartmann,  ^sthetik,  Bd.  ii,  Leipzig,  1887. 
Adolf    Hildebrand,  Das  Problem  der  Form  in  der  bildenden  Kunst.     3  Aufl. 

Strassburg,  1901 
Yrjo  Hirn,  The  Origins  of  Art,  London,  1900.  Deutsch,  Leipzig,  1904. 
Karl  Lange,  Sirmesgenusse  und  Kunstgenuss,  Wiesbaden,  1903. 
Konrad  Lange,  Das  Wesen  der  Kunst,  2  Bde.,  Berlin,  1901. 
Theodor  Lipps,  Raumsesthetik,  Leipzig,  1897.  —  Komik  und  Humor,  Hamburg 

imd  Leipzig,  1898.  —  Grundlegung  der  ^sthetik,  Hamburg  und  Leipzig,  1903. 
Cesare  Lombroso,  L'uomo  di  genio  in  rapporto  alia  psichiatria.    Torino,  1889 

und  ofter.     Deutsch,  Hamburg,  1890. 
H.  Rutgers  Marshall,  Esthetic  Principles,  New  York,  1895. 
A.  Meinong,  Ueber  Annahmen,  Leipzig,  1902. 
Th.  A.  Meyer,  Das  Stilgesetz  der  Poesie,  Leipzig,  1901. 
P.  J.  Mobius,  Ueber  Kunst  und  Kiinstler,  Leipzig,  1901. 
William  Mori'is,  Hopes  and  Fears  for  Art,  London,  1882.    Deutsch,  Bd.  i.  Die 

niederen  Kiinste.  ii.  Die  Kunst  des  Volkes.    Leipzig,  1891. 
Hugo  Mtinsterberg,  Harvard  Psychological  Studies.  Bd.  i,  Lancaster,  Pa.  1903. 
Ernst  Nemnann,  Untersuchungen  fur  Psychologic  und  ^sthetik  des  Rhythmus 

Philos.  Studien,  herausg.  von  W.  Wundt,  1894,  Bd.  x. 
John  Ruskin,  Ausgewahlte  Werke.  Deutsch,  Leipzig,  1900, 
G.  Sergi,  Dolore  e  Piacere,  Milano,  1897. 
Paul  Souriau,  L'esthetique  du  mouvement,  Paris,  1889. 
Herbert  Spencer,  Principles  of  Psychology,   Bd.  ii,  London,  1855  und    ofter. 

Deutsch,  Leipzig,  1875,  ff. 
Hugo  Spitzer,  Hermann  Hettners  Kunstphilosophische  Anfange,  Graz,  1903. 
H.  Taine,  Philosophie  de  I'Art.   2  Bde.   7  Aufl.  Paris,  1895. 
Leo  Tolstoj,  Was  ist  Kunst?    Deutsch,  Berlin,  1892. 
Johannes  Volkelt,-  ^sthetische  Zeitfragen,  Muenchen,  1895.     Deutch,  Leipzig, 

1902-03.— ^sthetik  des  Tragischen,  Munchen,  1897.— System  der^sthetik, 

Bd.  I,  Munchen,  1905. 
Stephan  Witasek,  Grundztige  der  allgemeinen  ^sthetik,  Leipzig. 
Wilheim  Wundt,  Grundziige  der  physiologsichen  Psychologie,  1904.  Bd.   iii.  5 

Aufl.  Leipzig,  1903. 


SHORT  PAPERS 

A  short  paper  was  contributed  by  Professor  A.  D.  F.  Hamlin,  of  Columbia 
University,  on  the  "Sources  of  Savage  Conventional  Patterns."  The  speaker 
said  that,  in  the  exhibit  of  the  Department  of  the  Interior,  two  glass  cases  displayed 
side  by  side  the  handiwork  of  the  American  Indian  of  one  hundred  years  ago  and 
of  to-day.  In  the  Fine  Arts  palace  the  blankets  and  basketry  of  the  Navahoes 
were  shown  beside  the  leather  work  and  other  handicrafts  of  white  Americans. 
In  both  instances  the  contrast  between  the  savage  and  the  civilized  work  em- 
phasizes the  fact  that  civilization  tends  to  stifle  or  destroy  the  decorative  instinct. 
The  savage  art  is  spontaneous,  instructive,  unpremeditated.  The  work  of  the 
civilized  artist  is  thoughtful,  carefully  elaborated,  intellectual.  Among  these 
peoples  both  the  crafts  and  the  patterns  are  traditional,  and  there  is  little  or  no 
ambition  to  innovate.  The  forms  and  combinations  we  admire  in  their  work  are 
the  result  of  long-continued  processes  of  evolution  and  elimination  in  which,  as  in 
the  world  of  Uving  organisms,  the  fittest  have  survived.  The  structure  of  savage 
patterns  is  almost  always  extremely  simple.  There  are  three  theories  advanced  to 
account  for  them;  that  they  were  invented  out  of  hand;  that  they  were  evolved 
out  of  the  technical  processes,  tools,  and  materials  of  primitive  industry;  that 
they  are  descended  from  fetish  or  animistic  representations  of  natural  forms. 
The  first  is  the  common  view  of  laymen;  the  second  was  first  expressed  (though 
chiefly  with  reference  to  civilized  art)  by  Semper;  and  the  third  is  widely  enter- 
tained by  anthropologists. 

The  savage  instinct  for  decoration  has  probably  developed  from  primitive 
animism  —  from  that  fear  of  the  powers  of  nature,  and  that  confounding  of  the 
animate  and  inanimate  world  which  is  universally  recognized  as  a  primitive 
trait.  But  once  awakened  in  even  the  sHghtest  degree,  it  has  found  exercise  in 
the  operations  of  primitive  industry,  and  given  existence  to  a  long  series  of  repeti- 
tive forms  produced  in  weaving,  basketry,  string-lashing,  and  car\ing.  The  two 
classes  of  patterns  thus  originated  —  those  derived  from  the  imitation  of  nature 
under  fetish  ideas,  and  those  derived  from  teclinical  processes  —  have  invariably 
converged,  overlapping  at  last  in  many  forms  of  decorative  art,  so  that  the  real 
origin  of  a  given  pattern  may  be  dual.  Myths  have  invariably  arisen  to  explain 
the  origin  of  the  technical  patterns,  which  have  received  magic  significance  and 
names,  in  accordance  with  savage  tendency  to  assign  magical  powers  to  all  visible 
or  at  least  to  all  valued  objects:  all  savage  art  is  talismanic.  One  ought  to  be 
cautious  about  dogmatizing  as  to  origins  in  dealing  with  savage  art,  because  both 
the  phenomenon  of  what  I  call  convergence  in  ornament  evolution,  and  that  of 
the  myths,  poetic  faculty,  and  habit  among  savages,  tend  to  confuse  and  obscure 
the  real  origin  of  the  patterns  with  which  they  deal.  And  finally,  for  the  artist 
as  distinguished  from  the  archaeologist  and  the  theorist,  the  real  lesson  of  savage 
art  is  not  in  its  origins,  but  in  its  products;  in  the  strength,  simplicity,  admirable 
distribution,  and  high  decorative  effects  of  poor  and  despised  peoples.  Savage 
aU-over  patterns  and  Greek  carved  ornament  and  decorative  sculpture  represent 
the  opposed  poles  of  decorative  design,  and  both  are  of  fundamental  value  as 
objects  of  study  for  the  designer. 


BIBLIOGRAPHY:  DEPARTMENT  OF   PHILOSOPHY 

PREPARED  THROUGH  THE  COURTESY  OF  DR. RALPH  BARTON  PERRY, 
-  OF  HARVARD  UNIVERSITY 

HISTORY  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

BouiLLiEB,  F.,  Philosophie  Cartesienne. 
Burnet,  J.,  Early  Greek  Philosophy. 
Erdmann,  J.  E.,  Geschichte  der  Philosophie. 
EucKEN,  R. ,  Lebensanschauungen  der  grossen  Denker. 
Fairbanks,  A.,  The  First  Philosophers  of  Greece. 
Falkenberg,  R.  ,  Geschichte  der  neueren  Philosophie. 
Fischer,  K.,  Geschichte  der  neueren  Philosophie. 
Gomperz,  Th.,  Greek  Thinkers. 
Hoffding,  H.,  Geschichte  der  neueren  Philosophie. 
Levy-Bruhl,  Histoire  de  la  philosophie  moderne. 
Royce,  J.,  Spirit  of  Modern  Philosophy. 
SiDGwiCK,  H.,  History  of  Ethics. 
Turner,  W.,  History  of  Philosophy. 
Ueberweg,  F.  ,  Geschichte  der  Philosophie. 
Weber,  A.,  Histoire  de  la  philosophie  europeenne. 
Windelband,  W.,  Geschichte  der  Philosophie. 

Geschichte  der  alten  Philosophie. 
Zeller,  E.,  Geschichte  der  griechischen  Philosophie. 

PHILOSOPHICAL   CLASSICS 

Abelard,  Dialectic. 

Anselm,  Monologium. 
Aristotle,  Metaphysics. 
De  Anima. 
Physics. 

Nicomachean  Ethics. 
Bacon,  F.,  Novum  Organum. 

Berkeley,  G.,  The  Principles  of  Human  Knowledge. 
Bruno,  G.,  Dialogi,  De  la  Causa  Principio  et  Uno,  etc. 
Burnet,  J.,  Early  Greek  Philosophy;  fragments  of  Heraclitus,  Parmenides, 

Anaxagoras,  etc. 
Descartes,  R.,  Discours  de  la  Methode. 

Meditationes  de  Prima  Philosophia. 
Duns  Scotus,  Opus  Oxoniense. 
FiCHTE,  J.  G.,  Wissenschaftslehre. 
Hegel,  G.  W.  F.,  Wissenschaft  der  Logik. 

Encyklopadie. 
Hobbes,  T.,  Leviathan.- 
Hume,  D.,  Enquiry  Concerning  the  Human  Understanding. 

Enquiry  Concerning  the  Principles  of  Morals. 
Kant,  I.,  Kritik  der  reinen  Vermmft. 

Kritik  der  praktischen  Vernunft. 
Kritik  der  Urteilskraft. 


450    BIBLIOGRAPHY:  DEPARTMENT  OF   PHILOSOPHY 

Leibniz,  G.  W.,  Monadologie. 

Theodicee. 
Locke,  J.,  An  Essay  Concerning  Human  Understanding. 
LoTZE,  R.  H.,  Metaphysik. 
Lucretius,  De  Rerum  Natura. 
Plato,    Republic.    Phaedo.    Theaetetus.    SsTnposium.    Phaedrus.    Protagoras 

(and  other  dialogues). 
Plotinus,  Enneades. 
St.  Augustine,  De  Civitate  Dei. 
ScHELLiNG,  Philosophic  der  Natur. 

Schopenhauer,  A.,  Die  Welt  als  Wille  und  Vorstellung. 
Spencer,  H.,  Synthetic  Philosophy. 
Spinoza,  B.,  Ethica. 
Thomas  Aquinas,  Summa  Theologiae. 

INTRODUCTION  TO  PHILOSOPHY 

Baldwin,  J.  M.,  Dictionary  of  Philosophy. 

Hibben,  J.  G.,  Problems  of  Philosophy. 

KuLPE,  0.,  Einleitung  in  die  Philosophic. 

Marvin,  W.  T.,  Introduction  to  Philosophy. 

Paulsen,  F.,  Einleitung  in  die  Philosophic. 

Perry,  R.  B.,  Approach  to  Philosophy. 

SiDGWicK,  H.,  Philosophy,  its  Scope  and  Relations. 

Stuckenberg,  J.  H.  W.,  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  Philosophy. 

Watson,  J.,  Outline  of  Philosophy. 

WiNDELBAND,  W.,  Praludien. 

METAPHYSICS 

AvENARius,  R.,  Kritik  der  reinen  Erfahrung. 

Bergson,  H.,  Matiere  et  memoire. 

Bradley,  F.  H.,  Appearance  and  Reality. 

Deussen,  p..  Elements  of  Metaphysics. 

Eucken,  R.,  Der  Kampf  um  einen  geistigen  Lebensinhalt. 

Fullerton,  G.  S.,  System  of  Metaphysics. 

Hodgson,  S.,  Metaphysics  of  Experience. 

HowisoN,  G.  H.,  The  Limits  of  Evolution. 

James,  W.,  The  Will  to  Believe. 

LiEBMANN,  Analysis  der  Wirklichkeit. 

Ormond,  a.  T.,  Foundations  of  Knowledge. 

Petzoldt,  J. ,  Philosophic  der  reinen  Erfahrung. 

Renouvier,  C,  Les  Dilemmes  de  la  m^taphysique  pure. 

Rickert,  H.,  Der  Gegenstand  der  Erkeuntniss. 

RiEHL,  A.,  Philosophische  Kriticismus. 

RoYCE,  J.,  The  World  and  the  Individual. 

Schiller,  F.  C.  S.,  Humanism. 

Seth,  A.,  Man  and  the  Cosmos. 

Sturt,  H.  (editor) ,  Personal  Idealism. 

Taylor,  A.  E.,  Elements  of  Metaphysics. 

VoLKELT,  J.,  Erfahrung  imd  Denken. 

WiNDELBAND,  W.,  Praludicn. 

WuNDT,  W.,  System  der  Philosophie. 


BIBLIOGRAPHY:  DEPARTMENT  OF    PHILOSOPHY     451 


PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELIGION 

BoussET,  W.,  Das  Wesen  der  Religion,  dargestellt  in  ihrer  Geschichte. 

Caird,  E.,  The  Evolution  of  Religion. 

DoRNER,  A.,  Religionsphilosophie. 

EucKEN,  R.,  Der  Wahrheitsgehalt  der  Religion. 

Everett,  C.  C,  The  Psychological  Elements  of  Religious  Faith. 

Hartmann,  von,  E.,  Religionsphilosophie. 

HoFFDiNG,  H.,  Religionsphilosophie. 

James,  W.,  Varieties  of  Religious  Experience. 

Martineau,  J.,  A  Study  of  Religion,  its  Sources  and  Contents. 

MtJLLER,  M.,  Einleitung  in  die  vergleichende  Religionswissenschaft. 

Pfleiderer,  O.,  Religionspliilosophie  auf  geschichtelichen  Grundlage. 

Rauenhopf,  Religionsphilosophie. 

RoYCE,  J.,  The  ReUgious  Aspect  of  Philosophy. 

Sabatier,  a.,   Religionsphilosophie  auf    psychologischen   und  geschichtUchen 

Grundlage. 
Saussaye,  Lehrbuch  der  Religionsgeschichte. 
Seydel,  R.,  Religionsphilosophie. 
Teichmuller,  G.,  Religionsphilosophie. 
Tiele,  C.  p.,  Grundziige  der  Religionswissenschaft. 

LOGIC 

Bradley,  F.  H.,  The  Principles  of  Logic. 

Bosanquet,  B.,  Logic. 

Cohen,  H.,  Die  Logik  der  reinen  Erkenntniss. 

Dewey,  J.,  Studies  in  Logical  Theory. 

Erdmann,  B.,  Logik. 

Hibben,  J.  G.,  Logic. 

HoBHOUSE,  L.  T.,  Theory  of  Knowledge. 

HussERL,  Logische  Untersuchungen. 

Lotze,  R.  H.,  Gnmdziige  der  Logik. 

ScHUPPE,  W.,  Erkenntnisstheoretische  Logik. 

SiGWART,  C,  Logik. 

Wundt,  W.,  Logik. 

METHODOLOGY  OF  SCIENCE 

Cantor,  G.,  Grundlagen  einer  allgemeinen  Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. 

Dedekind,  R.,  Was  sind  und  was  sollen  die  Zahlen?  . 

Hertz,  H.,  Die  Principien  der  Mechanik. 

Jevons,  W.  S.,  Principles  of  Science. 

Mach,  E.,  Die  Analyse  der  Empfindung. 

Munsterberg,  H.,  Grtmdziige  der  Psychologie. 

Natorp,  p.,  Einleitimg  in  die  Psychologie. 

OsTWALD,  W.,  Vorlesungen  iiber  Naturphilosophie. 

Pearson,  K.,  Grammar  of  Science. 

Poincare,  H.,  La  Science  et  I'Hypoth^se. 

Rickert,  H.  ,  Die  Grenzen  der  naturwissenschaftlichen  Begriffsbildung.  . 

RoYCE,  J.,  The  World  and  the  Individual,  Second  Series. 

Russell,  B.,  The  Principles  of  Mathematics. 

Ward,  J.,  Naturalism  and  Agnosticism. 

Windelband,  W.,  Geschichte  und  Naturwissenschaft. 


452    BIBLIOGRAPHY:  DEPARTMENT   OF    PHILOSOPHY 


ETHICS 

Alexander,  S.,  Moral  Order  and  Progress. 

Bradley,  F.  H.,  Ethical  Studies. 

Cohen,  H.  ,  Ethik  des  reinen  Willens. 

GiZYCKi,  G.,  Grundziige  der  Moral. 

Green,  T.  H.  ,  Prolegomena  to  Ethics. 

GuYAU,  M.  J.,  Esquisse  d'une  morale  sans  obligation  ni  sanction. 

Ladd,  G.  T.,  Philosophy  of  Conduct. 

Martineau,  J.,  Types  of  Ethical  Theory. 

Mezes,  S.  E.,  Ethics,  Descriptive  and  Explanatory. 

Moore,  G.  E.,  Principia  Etbica. 

Palmer,  G.  H.,  The  Nature  of  Goodness. 

Paulsen,  F.,  System  der  Ethik. 

RoYCE,  J.,  Studies  of  Good  and  Evil. 

Seth,  J.,  Principles  of  Ethics. 

Sidgwick,  H.,  Methods  of  Ethics. 

SiMMEL,  G.,  Einleitimg  in  die  Moralwissenschaft. 

SoRLEY,  W.  E..,  Ethics  of  Naturalism. 

Spencer,  H.,  Principles  of  Ethics. 

Stephen,  L.,  Science  of  Ethics. 

Taylor,  A.  E.,  The  Problem  of  Conduct. 

Wundt,  W.,  Ethik. 

ESTHETICS 

Cohn,  Allgemeine  iRsthetik. 

GuYAU,  M.  J.,  Les  Problemes  de  I'esthetique  contemporaine. 

HiRN,  Yrjo,  The  Origins  of  Art. 

Lange,  K.,  Das  Wesen  der  Kunst. 

Lipps,  T.,  ^sthetik. 

Puffer,  E.,  Psychology  of  Beauty. 

SouRiAU,  P.,  La  Beauts  Rationelle. 

Volkelt,  J.,  System  der  jEsthetik. 

Witasek,  S.,  Grundziige  der  allgemeinen  sesthetik. 


DEPARTMENT  II  —  MATHEMATICS 


DEPARTMENT  II  —  MATHEMATICS 


{Hall  7,  September  20,  11.15  a.  m.) 

Chairman:     Peofessor  Henry  S.  White,  Northwestern  University. 
Speaxers:     Professor  Maxime  Bocher,  Harvard  University. 
Professor  James  P.  Pierpont,  Yale  University. 

The  Chairman  of  the  Department  of  Mathematics  was  Professor 
Henry  S.  White,  of  Northwestern  University.  In  opening  the  pro- 
ceedings Professor  White  said: 

"  Influenced  by  patriotism  and  by  pride  in  material  progress,  cities 
and  whole  nations  meet  and  celebrate  the  building  of  bridges,  the 
opening  of  long  railways,  the  tunneling  of  difficult  mountain  passes, 
the  acquisition  of  new  territories,  or  commemorate  with  festivity  the 
discovery  of  a  continent.  These  things  are  real  and  significant  to  us 
all. 

"  In  the  realm  of  ideas  also  there  are  events  of  no  less  moment, 
discoveries  and  conquests  that  greatly  enlarge  the  empire  of  human 
reason.  In  the  lapse  of  a  century  there  may  be  many  such  notable 
achievements,  even  in  the  domain  of  a  single  science. 

"  Mathematics  is  a  science  continually  expanding;  and  its  growth, 
unlike  some  political  and  industrial  events,  is  attended  by  universal 
acclamation.  We  are  wont  to-day,  as  devotees  of  this  noble  and 
useful  science,  to  pass  in  review  the  newest  phases  of  her  expansion, 
—  I  say  newest,  for  in  retrospect  a  century  is  but  brief,  —  and  to 
rejoice  in  the  deeds  of  the  past.  At  the  same  time,  also,  we  turn 
an  eye  of  aspiration  and  resolution  towards  the  mountains,  rivers, 
deserts,  and  the  obstructing  seas  that  are  to  test  the  mathematicians 
of  the  future." 


THE   FUNDAMENTAL   CONCEPTIONS   AND   METHODS   OF 

MATHEMATICS 

BY    PROFESSOR    MAXIME    BQCHER 

[Maxime  Bocher,  Professor  of  Mathematics,  Harvard  University,  b.  August  28, 
1867,  Boston,  Mass.  A.B.  Harvard,  1888;  Ph.D.  Gottingen,  1891.  In- 
structor, Assistant  Professor  and  Professor,  Harvard  University,  1891-. 
Fellow  of  the  American  Academy.  Author  of  Ueber  die  Reihenentwickel- 
ungen  der  Potentialtheorie;  and  various  papers  on  mathematics.] 

I.  Old  and  New  Definitions  of  Mathematics 

I  AM  going  to  ask  you  to  spend  a  few  minutes  with  me  in  consider- 
ing the  question:  what  is  mathematics?  In  doing  this  I  do  not  propose 
to  lay  down  dogmatically  a  precise  definition;  but  rather,  after  hav- 
ing pointed  out  the  inadequacy  of  traditional  views,  to  determine 
what  characteristics  are  common  to  the  most  varied  parts  of  mathe- 
matics but  are  not  shared  by  other  sciences,  and  to  show  how  this 
opens  the  way  to  two  or  three  definitions  of  mathematics,  any  one  of 
which  is  fairly  satisfactory.  Although  this  is,  after  all,  merely  a  dis- 
cussion of  the  meaning  to  be  attached  to  a  name,  I  do  not  think  that 
it  is  unfruitful,  since  its  aim  is  to  bring  unity  into  the  fundamental 
conceptions  of  the  science  with  which  we  are  concerned.  If  any  of 
you,  however,  should  regard  such  a  discussion  of  the  meaning  of  words 
as  devoid  of  any  deeper  significance,  I  will  ask  you  to  regard  this 
question  as  merely  a  bond  by  means  of  which  I  have  found  it  con- 
venient to  unite  what  I  have  to  say  on  the  fundamental  conceptions 
and  methods  of  what,  with  or  without  definition,  we  all  of  us  agree 
to  call  mathematics. 

The  old  idea  that  mathematics  is  the  science  of  quantity,  or  that 
it  is  the  science  of  space  and  number,  or  indeed  that  it  can  be  charac- 
terized by  any  enumeration  of  several  more  or  less  heterogeneous 
objects  of  study,  has  pretty  well  passed  away  among  those  mathe- 
maticians who  have  given  any  thought  to  the  question  of  what 
mathematics  really  is.  Such  definitions,  which  might  have  been 
intelligently  defended  at  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth  century, 
became  obviously  inadequate  as  subjects  like  projective  geometry, 
the  algebra  of  logic,  and  the  theory  of  abstract  groups  were  de- 
veloped; for  none  of  these  has  any  necessary  relation  to  quantity 
(at  least  in  any  ordinary  understanding  of  that  word),  and  the  last 
two  have  no  relation  to  space.  It  is  true  that  such  examples  have 
had  little  effect  on  the  more  or  less  orthodox  followers  of  Kant, 
who  regard  mathematics  as  concerned  with  those  conceptions  which 


CONCEPTIONS   AND  METHODS   OF  MATHEMATICS     457 

are  obtained  by  direct  intuition  of  time  and  space  without  the  aid  of 
empirical  observation.  This  view  seems  to  have  been  held  by  such 
eminent  mathematicians  as  Hamilton  and  DeMorgan;  and  it  is  a 
very  difficult  position  to  refute,  resting  as  it  does  on  a  purely  meta- 
physical foundation  which  regards  it  as  certain  that  we  can  evolve 
out  of  our  inner  consciousness  the  properties  of  time  and  space. 
According  to  this  view  the  idea  of  quantity  is  to  be  deduced  from 
these  intuitions;  but  one  of  the  facts  most  vividly  brought  home  to 
pure  mathematicians  during  the  last  half-century  is  the  fatal  weak- 
ness of  intuition  when  taken  as  the  logical  source  of  our  knowledge 
of  number  and  quantity.^ 

The  objects  of  mathematical  study,  even  when  we  confine  our 
attention  to  what  is  ordinarily  regarded  as  pure  mathematics  are, 
then,  of  the  most  varied  description;  so  that,  in  order  to  reach  a 
satisfactory  conclusion  as  to  what  really  characterizes  mathematics, 
one  of  two  methods  is  open  to  us.  On  the  one  hand  we  may  seek 
some  hidden  resemblance  in  the  various  objects  of  mathematical 
investigation,  and  having  found  an  aspect  common  to  them  all  we 
may  fix  on  this  as  the  one  true  object  of  mathematical  study.  Or, 
on  the  other  hand,  we  may  abandon  the  attempt  to  characterize 
mathematics  by  means  of  its  objects  of  study,  and  seek  in  its  methods 
its  distinguishing  characteristic.  Finally,  there  is  the  possibility  of 
our  combining  these  two  points  of  view.  The  first  of  these  methods  is 
that  of  Kempe,  the  second  will  lead  us  to  the  definition  of  Benjamin 
Peirce,  while  the  third  has  recently  been  elaborated  at  great  length 
by  Russell.  Other  mathematicians  have  naturally  followed  out  more 
or  less  consistently  the  same  ideas,  but  I  shall  nevertheless  take  the 
liberty  of  using  the  names  Kempe,  Peirce,  and  Russell  as  convenient 
designations  for  these  three  points  of  view.  These  different  methods 
of  approaching  the  question  lead  finally  to  results  which,  without 
being  identical,  still  stand  in  the  most  intimate  relation  to  one  an- 
other, as  we  shall  now  see.    Let  us  begin  with  the  second  method. 

II.   Peirce' s  Definition 

More  than  a  third  of  a  century  ago  Benjamin  Peirce  wrote:  ^ 
Mathematics  is  the  science  which  draws  necessary  conclusions.  Accord- 
ing to  this  view  there  is  a  mathematical  element  involved  in  every 
inquiry  in  which  exact  reasoning  is  used.  Thus,  for  instance,^  a 
jury  listening  to  the  attempt  of  the  counsel  for  the  prisoner  to  prove 
an  alibi  in  a  criminal  case  might  reason  as  follows:  "If  the  witnesses 

'  I  refer  here  to  such  facts  as  that  there  exist  continuous  functions  without 
derivatives,  whereas  the  direct  untutored  intuition  of  space  would  lead  anj^  one 
to  believe  that  every  continuous  curve  has  tangents. 

^  Linear  Associative  Algebra.  Lithographed  1870.  Reprinted  in  the  American 
Journal  of  Mathematics,  vol.  iv. 

3  This  illustration  was  suggested  by  the  remarks  by  J.  Richard,  Sur  la  philoso- 
phie  des  mathmeatiques.  Paris,  Gauthier-Villars,  1903^  p.  50. 


458  MATHEMATICS 

are  telling  the  truth  when  they  say  that  the  prisoner  was  in  St.  Louis 
at  the  moment  the  crime  was  committed  in  Chicago,  and  if  it  is 
true  that  a  person  cannot  be  in  two  places  at  the  same  time,  it  follows 
that  the  prisoner  was  not  in  Chicago  when  the  crime  was  committed." 
This,  according  to  Peirce,  is  a  bit  of  mathematics;  while  the  further 
reasoning  by  which  the  jury  would  decide  whether  or  not  to  believe 
the  witnesses,  and  the  reasoning  (if  they  thought  any  necessary) 
by  which  they  would  satisfy  themselves  that  a  person  cannot  be 
in  two  places  at  once,  would  be  inductive  reasoning,  which  can  give 
merely  a  high  degree  of  probability  to  the  conclusion,  but  never 
certainty.  This  mathematical  element  may  be,  as  the  example 
just  given  shows,  so  slight  as  not  to  be  worth  noticing  from  a  prac- 
tical point  of  view.  This  is  almost  always  the  case  in  the  transac- 
tions of  daily  life  and  in  the  observational  sciences.  If,  however,  we 
turn  to  such  subjects  as  chemistry  and  mineralogy,  we  find  the 
mathematical  element  of  considerable  importance,  though  still 
subordinate.  In  physics  and  astronomy  its  importance  is  much 
greater.  Finally  in  geometry,  to  mention  only  one  other  science,  the 
mathematical  element  predominates  to  such  an  extent  that  this 
science  has  been  commonly  rated  a  branch  of  pure  mathematics, 
whereas,  according  to  Peirce,  it  is  as  much  a  branch  of  applied 
mathematics  as  is,  for  instance,  mathematical  physics. 

It  is  clear  from  what  has  just  been  said  that,  from  Peirce's  point 
of  view,  mathematics  does  not  necessarily  concern  itself  with  quanti- 
tative relations,  and  that  any  subject  becomes  capable  of  mathe- 
matical treatment  as  soon  as  it  has  secured  data  from  which  import- 
ant consequences  can  be  drawn  by  exact  reasoning.  Thus,  for 
example,  even  though  psychologists  be  right  when  they  assure  us 
that  sensations  and  the  other  objects  with  which  they  have  to  deal 
cannot  be  measured,  we  need  still  not  necessarily  despair  of  one  day 
seeing  a  mathematical  psychology,  just  as  we  already  have  a  math- 
ematical logic. 

I  have  said  enough,  I  think,  to  show  what  relation  Peirce's  con- 
ception of  mathematics  has  to  the  applications.  Let  us  then  turn 
to  the  definition  itself  and  examine  it  a  little  more  closely.  You 
have  doubtless  already  noticed  that  the  phrase,  "  the  science  which 
draws  necessary  conclusions, "  contains  a  word  which  is  very  much 
in  need  of  elucidation.  What  is  a  necessary  conclusion?  Some  of 
you  will  perhaps  think  that  the  conception  here  involved  is  one 
about  which,  in  a  concrete  case  at  least,  there  can  be  no  practical 
diversity  of  opinion  among  men  with  well-trained  minds;  and  in 
fact  when  I  spoke  a  few  minutes  ago  about  the  reasoning  of  the 
jurymen  when  listening  to  the  lawyer  trying  to  prove  an  alibi,  I 
assumed  tacitly  that  this  is  so.  If  this  really  were  the  case,  no  further 
discussion  would  be  necessary,  for  it  is  not  my  purpose  to  enter  into 


CONCEPTIONS   AND   METHODS   OF   MATHEMATICS     459 

any  purely  philosophical  speculations.  But  unfortunately  we  can- 
not dismiss  the  matter  in  this  way;  for  it  has  happened  not  infre- 
quently that  the  most  eminent  men,  including  mathematicians, 
have  differed  as  to  whether  a  given  piece  of  reasoning  was  exact  or 
not;  and,  what  is  worse,  modes  of  reasoning  which  seem  absolutely 
conclusive  to  one  generation  no  longer  satisfy  the  next,  as  is  shown 
by  the  way  in  which  the  greatest  mathematicians  of  the  eighteenth 
century  used  geometric  intuition  as  a  means  of  drawing  what  they 
regarded  as  necessary  conclusions.^ 

1  do  not  wish  here  to  raise  the  question  whether  there  is  such  a 
thing  as  absolute  logical  rigor,  or  whether  this  whole  conception  of 
logical  rigor  is  a  purely  psychological  one  bound  to  change  with 
changes  in  the  human  mind.  I  content  myself  with  expressing  the 
belief,  which  I  will  try  to  justify  a  little  more  fully  in  a  moment, 
that  as  we  never  have  found  an  immutable  standard  of  logical  rigor 
in  the  past,  so  we  are  not  hkely  to  find  it  in  the  future.  However 
this  may  be,  so  much  we  can  say  with  tolerable  confidence,  as  past 
experience  shows,  that  no  reasoning  which  claims  to  be  exact  can 
make  any  use  of  intuition,  but  that  it  must  proceed  from  definitely 
and  completely  stated  premises  according  to  certain  principles  of 
formal  logic.  It  is  right  here  that  modern  mathematicians  break 
sharply  with  the  tradition  of  a  'priori  synthetic  judgments  (that  is, 
conclusions  drawn  from  intuition)  which,  according  to  Kant,  form  an 
essential  part  of  mathematical  reasoning. 

If  then  we  agree  that  "  necessary  conclusions  "  must,  in  the  present 
state  of  human  knowledge,  mean  conclusions  drawn  according  to 
certain  logical  principles  from  definitely  and  completely  stated 
premises,  we  must  face  the  question  as  to  what  these  principles 
shall  be.  Here,  fortunately,  the  mathematical  logicians  from  Boole 
down  to  C.  S.  Peirce,  Schroder,  and  Peano  have  prepared  the  field 
so  well  that  of  late  years  Peano  and  his  followers  ^  have  been  able 
to  make  a  rather  short  list  of  logical  conceptions  and  principles  upon 
which  it  would  seem  that  all  exact  reasoning  depends.^  We  must 
remember,  however,  when  we  are  tempted  to  put  implicit  confidence 
in  certain  fundamental  logical  principles,  that,  owing  to  their  extreme 
generality  and  abstractness,  no  very  great  weight  can  be  attached 
to  the  mere  fact  that  these  principles  appeal  to  us  as  obviously 

^  All  writers  on  elementary  geometry  from  Euclid  down  almost  to  the  close 
of  the  nineteenth  century  use  intuition  freely,  though  usually  unconsciously,  in 
obtaining  results  which  they  are  unable  to  deduce  from  their  axioms.  The  first 
few  demonstrations  of  Euclid  are  criticised  from  this  point  of  view  by  Russell  in 
his  Principles  of  Mathematics,  vol.  i,  404-407.  Gauss's  first  proof  (1799)  that 
every  algebraic  equation  has  a  root  gives  a  striking  example  of  the  use  of  intuition 
in  what  was  intended  as  an  absolutely  rigorous  proof  by  one  of  the  greatest  and  at 
the  same  time  most  critical  mathematical  minds  the  world  has  ever  seen. 

^  And,  independently,  Frege. 

2  It  is  not  intended  to  assert  that  a  single  list  has  been  fixed  upon.  Different 
writers  naturally  use  different  lists. 


460  MATHEMATICS 

true;  for,  as  I  have  said,  other  modes  of  reasoning  which  are  now 
universally  recognized  as  faulty  have  appealed  in  just  this  way  to 
the  greatest  minds  of  the  past.  Such  confidence  as  we  feel  must, 
I  think,  come  from  the  fact  that  those  modes  of  reasoning  which 
we  trust  have  withstood  the  test  of  use  in  an  immense  number  of 
cases  and  in  very  many  fields.  This  is  the  severest  test  to  which  any 
theory  can  be  put,  and  if  it  does  not  break  down  under  it  we  may 
feel  the  greatest  confidence  that,  at  least  in  cognate  fields,  it  will 
prove  serviceable.  But  we  can  never  be  sure.  The  accepted  modes 
of  exact  reasoning  may  any  day  lead  to  a  contradiction  which  would 
show  that  what  we  regard  as  universally  applicable  principles  are 
in  reality  applicable  only  under  certain  restrictions.^ 

To  show  that  the  danger  which  I  here  point  out  is  not  a  purely 
fanciful  one,  it  is  sufiicient  to  refer  to  a  very  recent  example.  Inde- 
pendently of  one  another,  Frege  and  Russell  have  built  up  the  theory 
of  arithmetic  from  its  logical  foundations.  Each  starts  with  a  definite 
list  of  apparently  self-evident  logical  principles,  and  builds  up  a 
seemingly  flawless  theory.  Then  Russell  discovers  that  his  logical 
principles  when  applied  to  a  very  general  kind  of  logical  class  lead 
to  an  absurdity;  and  both  Frege  and  Russell  have  to  admit  that 
something  is  wrong  with  the  foundations  which  looked  so  secure. 
Now  there  is  no  doubt  that  these  logical  foundations  will  be  somehow 
recast  to  meet  this  difficulty,  and  that  they  will  then  be  stronger 
than  ever  before. ^  But  who  shall  say  that  the  same  thing  will  not 
happen  again? 

It  is  commonly  considered  that  mathematics  owes  its  certainty 
to  its  reliance  on  the  immutable  principles  of  formal  logic.  This, 
as  we  have  seen,  is  only  half  the  truth  imperfectly  expressed.  The 
other  half  would  be  that  the  principles  of  formal  logic  owe  such 
degree  of  permanence  as  they  have  largely  to  the  fact  that  they 
have  been  tempered  by  long  and  varied  use  by  mathematicians. 
"A  vicious  circle!"  you  will  perhaps  say.  I  should  rather  describe 
it  as  an  example  of  the  process  known  to  mathematicians  as  the 
method  of  successive  approximations.  Let  us  hope  that  in  this 
case  it  is  really  a  convergent  process,  as  it  has  every  appearance  of 
being. 

But  to  return  to  Peirce's  definition.    From  what  are  these  neces- 

*  If  the  view  which  I  here  maintain  is  correct,  it  follows  that  if  the  teim  "  abso- 
lute logical  rigor"  has  a  meaning,  and  if  we  should  some  time  arrive  at  this  abso- 
lute standard,  the  only  indication  we  should  ever  have  of  the  fact  would  be  that 
for  a  long  period,  several  thousand  years  let  us  say,  the  logical  principles  in  ques- 
tion had  stood  the  test  of  use.  But  this  state  of  affairs  might  equally  well  mean 
that  during  that  time  the  human  mind  had  degenerated,  at  least  with  regard  to 
some  of  its  functions.  Consider,  for  instance,  the  twenty  centuries  following  Euclid 
when,  without  doubt,  the  high  tide  of  exact  thinking  attained  during  Euclid's  gen- 
eration had  receded. 

^  Cf.  Poincard's  view*  in  La  Science  et  I'Hypothese,  p.  179,  according  to  which 
a  theory  never  renders  a  greater  service  to  science  than  when  it  breaks  down. 


CONCEPTIONS   AND  METHODS   OF   MATHEMATICS    461 

sary  conclusions  to  be  drawn?  The  answer  clearly  implied  is,  from 
any  premises  sufficiently  precise  to  make  it  possible  to  draw  neces- 
sary conclusions  from  them.  In  geometry,  for  instance,  we  have  a 
large  number  of  intuitions  and  fixed  beliefs  concerning  the  nature 
of  space:  it  is  homogeneous  and  isotropic,  infinite  in  extent  in  every 
direction,  etc.;  but  none  of  these  ideas,  however  clearly  defined 
they  may  at  first  sight  seem  to  be,  gives  any  hold  for  exact  reasoning. 
This  was  clearly  perceived  by  Euclid,  who  therefore  proceeded  to 
lay  down  a  list  of  axioms  and  postulates,  that  is,  specific  facts  which 
he  assumes  to  be  true,  and  from  which  it  was  his  object  to  deduce  all 
geometric  propositions.  That  his  success  here  was  not  complete 
is  now  well  known,  for  he  frequently  assumes  unconsciously  further 
data  which  he  derives  from  intuition;  but  his  attempt  was  a  monu- 
mental one, 

III.  The  Abstract  Nature  of  Mathematics 

Now  a  further  self-evident  point,  but  one  to  which  attention  seems 
to  have  been  drawn  only  during  the  last  few  years,  is  this :  since  we 
are  to  make  no  use  of  intuition,  but  only  of  a  certain  number  of 
explicitly  stated  premises,  it  is  not  necessary  that  we  should  have 
any  idea  what  the  nature  of  the  objects  and  relations  involved  in 
these  premises  is.^  I  will  try  to  make  this  clear  by  a  simple  example. 
In  plane  geometry  we  have  to  consider,  among  other  things,  points  and 
straight  lines.  A  point  may  have  a  peculiar  relation  to  a  straight 
line  which  we  express  by  the  words,  the  point  lies  on  the  line.  Now 
one  of  the  fundamental  facts  of  plane  geometry  is  that  two  points 
determine  a  line,  that  is,  if  two  points  are  given,  there  exists  one  and 
only  one  line  on  which  both  points  lie.  All  the  facts  that  I  have  just 
stated  correspond  to  clear  intuitions.  Let  us,  however,  eliminate  our 
intuition  of  what  is  meant  by  a  point,  a  line,  a  point  lying  on  a  line. 
A  slight  change  of  language  will  make  it  easy  for  us  to  do  this.  In- 
stead of  points  and  lines,  let  us  speak  of  two  different  kinds  of  objects, 
say  A-objects  and  J5-objects;  and  instead  of  saying  that  a  point 
lies  on  a  line  we  will  simply  say  that  an  A-object  bears  a  certain 
relation  R  to  a,  jB-object.  Then  the  fact  that  two  points  determine 
a  line  will  be  expressed  by  saying:  If  any  two  ^-objects  are  given, 
there  exists  one  and  only  one  5-object  to  which  they  both  bear  the 
relation  R.  This  statement,  while  it  does  not  force  on  us  any  specific 
intuitions,  will  serve  as  a  basis  for  mathematical  reasoning  ^  just  as 
well  as  the  more  familiar  statement  where  the  terms  points  and  lines 

^  This  was  essentially  Kempe's  point  of  view  in  the  papers  to  be  referred  to 
presently.  In  the  geometric  example  which  follows  it  was  clearly  brought  out 
by  H.  Wiener:  Jahresbericht  d.  deuischen  Mathematiker-Vereinigung,  vol.  i  (1891), 
p.  45. 

^  In  conjunction,  of  course,  with  further  postulates  with  which  we  need  not 
here  concern  ourselves. 


462  MATHEMATICS 

are  used.  But  more  than  this.  Our  ^-objects,  our  B-objects,  and  our 
relation  R  may  be  given  an  interpretation,  if  we  choose,  very  different 
from  that  we  had  at  first  intended. 

We  may,  for  instance,  regard  the  A-objects  as  the  straight  hnes  in 
a  plane,  the  jB-objects  as  the  points  in  the  same  plane  (either  finite 
or  at  infinity),  and  when  an  A-object  stands  in  the  relation  jR  to  a 
5-object,  this  may  be  taken  to  mean  that  the  line  passes  through  the 
point.  Our  statement  would  then  become :  Any  two  lines  being  given, 
there  exists  one  and  only  one  point  through  which  they  both  pass. 
Or  we  may  regard  the  A-objects  as  the  men  in  a  certain  community, 
the  5-objects  as  the  women,  and  the  relation  of  an  A-object  to  a 
5-object  as  friendship.  Then  our  statement  would  be:  In  this  com- 
munity any  two  men  have  one,  and  only  one,  woman  friend  in  com- 
mon. 

These  examples  are,  I  think,  sufficient  to  show  what  is  meant 
when  I  say  that  we  are  not  concerned  in  mathematics  with  the 
nature  of  the  objects  and  relations  involved  in  our  premises,  except 
in  so  far  as  their  nature  is  exhibited  in  the  premises  themselves. 
Accordingly  mathematicians  of  a  critical  turn  of  mind,  during  the 
last  few  years,  have  adopted  more  and  more  a  purely  nominalistic 
attitude  towards  the  objects  and  relations  involved  in  mathematical 
investigation.  This  is,  of  course,  not  the  crude  mixture  of  nominalism 
and  empiricism  of  the  philosopher  Hobbes,  whose  claim  to  mathe- 
matical fame,  it  may  be  said  in  passing,  is  that  of  a  circle-squarer.^ 
The  nominalism  of  the  present-day  mathematician  consists  in  treating 
the  objects  of  his  investigation  and  the  relations  between  them  as 
mere  symbols.  He  then  states  his  propositions,  in  effect,  in  the  fol- 
lowing form:  If  there  exist  any  objects  in  the  physical  or  mental 
world  with  relations  among  themselves  which  satisfy  the  conditions 
which  I  have  laid  down  for  my  symbols,  then  such  and  such  facts 
will  be  true  concerning  them. 

It  will  be  seen  that,  according  to  Peirce's  view,  the  mathematician 
as  such  is  in  no  wise  concerned  with  the  source  of  his  premises  or  with 
their  harmony  or  lack  of  harmony  with  any  part  of  the  external 
world.  He  does  not  even  assert  that  any  objects  really  exist  which 
correspond  to  his  symbols.  Mathematics  may  therefore  be  truly 
said  to  be  the  most  abstract  of  all  sciences,  since  it  does  not  deal 
directly  with  reality.^ 

ThiS;  then,  is  Peirce's  definition  of  mathematics.  Its  advantages 
in  the  direction  of  unifying  our  conception  of  mathematics  and  of 
assigning  to  it  a  definite  place  among  the  other  sciences  are  clear. 

^  Hobbes  practically  obtains  as  the  ratio  of  a  circumference  to  its  diameter 
the  value  VlO.  Cf.  for  instance  Molesworth's  edition  of  Hobbes's  English  Works, 
vol.  VII,  p.  431. 

^  Cf.  the  very  interesting  remarks  along  this  line  of  C.  S.  Peirce  in  The  Monist, 
vol.  VII,  pp.  23-24. 


CONCEPTIONS   AND   METHODS   OF  MATHEMATICS    463 

What  are  its  disadvantages?  I  can  see  only  two.  First  that,  as  has 
been  already  remarked,  the  idea  of  drawing  necessary  conclusions 
is  a  slightly  vague  and  shifting  one.  Secondly,  that  it  lays  exclusive 
stress  on  the  rigorous  logical  element  in  mathematics  and  ignores 
the  intuitional  and  other  non-rigorous  tendencies  which  form  an 
important  element  in  the  great  bulk  of  mathematical  work  concern- 
ing which  I  shall  speak  in  greater  detail  later. 

IV.  Geometry  an  Experimental  Science 

Some  of  you  will  also  regard  it  as  an  objection  that  there  are 
subjects  which  have  almost  universally  been  regarded  as  branches 
of  mathematics  but  are  excluded  by  this  definition.  A  striking 
example  of  this  is  geometry,  I  mean  the  science  of  the  actual  space 
we  hve  in;  for  though  geometry  is,  according  to  Peirce's  definition, 
preeminently  a  mathematical  science,  it  is  not  exclusively  so.  Until 
a  system  of  axioms  is  established  mathematics  cannot  begin  its  work. 
Moreover,  the  actual  perception  of  spatial  relations,  not  merel}^ 
in  simple  cases  but  in  the  appreciation  of  complicated  theorems,  is 
an  essential  element  in  geometry  which  has  no  relation  to  mathe- 
matics as  Peirce  understands  the  term.  The  same  is  true,  to  a  con- 
siderable extent,  of  such  subjects  as  mechanical  drawing  and  model- 
making,  which  involve,  besides  small  amounts  of  physics  and  math- 
ematics, mainly  non-mathematical  geometry.  Moreover,  although  the 
mathematical  method  is  the  traditional  one  for  arriving  at  the  truth 
concerning  geometric  facts,  it  is  not  the  only  one.  Direct  appeal  to 
the  intuition  is  often  a  short  and  fairly  safe  cut  to  geometric  results; 
and  on  the  other  hand  experiments  may  be  used  in  geometry,  just 
as  they  are  used  every  day  in  physics,  to  test  the  truth  of  a  proposi- 
tion or  to  determine  the  value  of  some  geometric  magnitude.^ 

We  must,  then,  admit,  if  we  hold  to  Peirce's  view,  that  there  is 
an  independent  science  of  geometry  just  as  there  is  an  independent 
science  of  physics,  and  that  either  of  these  may  be  treated  by  math- 
ematical methods.  Thus  geometry  becomes  the  simplest  of  the 
natural  sciences,  and  its  axioms  are  of  the  nature  of  physical  laws, 
to  be  tested  by  experience  and  to  be  regarded  as  true  only  within 
the  limits  of  error  of  observation.  This  view,  while  it  has  not  yet 
gained  universal  recognition,  should,  I  believe,  prevail,  and  geo- 
metry be  recognized  as  a  science  independent  of  mathematics,  just 
as  psychology  is  gradually  being  recognized  as  an  independent 
science  and  not  as  a  branch  of  philosophy. 

The  view  here  set  'forth,  according  to  which  geometry  is  an  ex- 
perimental science  like  physics  or  chemistry,  has  been  held  ever 

1  I  am  thinking  of  measurements  and  observations  made  on  accurately  con- 
structed drawings  and  models.  A  famous  example  is  Galileo's  determination  of 
the  area  of  a  cycloid  by  cutting  out  a  cycloid  from  a  metallic  sheet  and  weighing  it. 


464  MATHEMATICS 

since  Gauss's  time  by  almost  all  the  leading  mathematicians  who 
have  been  conversant  with  non-Euclidean  geometry.^  Recently, 
however,  Poincare  has  thrown  the  weight  of  his  great  authority 
against  this  view,^  claiming  that  the  experiments  by  which  it  is 
sought  to  test  the  truth  of  geometric  axioms  are  really  not  geometrical 
experiments  at  all  but  physical  ones,  and  that  any  failure  of  these 
experiments  to  agree  with  the  ordinary  geometrical  axioms  could 
be  explained  by  the  inaccuracy  of  the  physical  laws  ordinarily  as- 
sumed. There  is  undoubtedly  an  important  element  of  truth  here. 
Every  experiment  depends  for  its  results  not  merely  on  the  law  Vv^e 
wish  to  test,  but  also  on  other  laws  which  for  the  moment  we  assume 
to  be  true.  But,  if  we  prefer,  we  may,  in  many  cases,  assume  as 
true  the  law  we  were  before  testing  and  our  experiment  will  then 
serve  to  test  some  of  the  remaining  laws.  If,  then,,  we  choose  to  stick 
to  the  ordinary  Euclidean  axioms  of  geometry  in  spite  of  what  any 
future  experiments  may  possibly  show,  we  can  do  so,  but  at  the  cost, 
perhaps,  of  our  present  simple  physical  laws,  not  merely  in  one 
branch  of  physics  but  in  several.  Poincare's  view  ^  is  that  it  will 
always  be  expedient  to  preserve  simple  geometric  laws  at  all  costs, 
an  opinion  for  which  I  fail  to  see  sufficient  reason. 

V,  Kemipe's  Definition 

Let  us  now  turn  from  Peirce's  method  of  defining  mathematics  to 
Kempe's,  which,  however,  I  shall  present  to  you  in  a  somewhat 
modified  form.*  The  point  of  view  adopted  here  is  to  try  to  define 
mathematics,  as  other  sciences  are  defined,  by  describing  the  objects 
with  which  it  deals.  The  diversity  of  the  objects  with  which  mathe- 
matics is  ordinarily  supposed  to  deal  being  so  great,  the  first  step 
must  be  to  divest  them  of  what  is  unessential  for  the  mathematical 
treatment,  and  to  try  in  this  way  to  discover  their  common  and 
characteristic  element. 

The  first  point  on  which  Kempe  insists  is  that  the  objects  of  mathe- 
matical discussion,  whether  they  be  the  points  and  fines  of  geometry, 
the  numbers  real  or  complex  of  algebra  or  analysis,  the  elements  of 
groups  or  anything  else,  are  always  individuals,  infinite  in  number 
perhaps,  but  still  distinct  individuals.  In  a  particular  mathematical 
investigation  we  may,  and  usually  do,  have  several  different  kinds  of 
individuals;  as  for  instance,  in  elementary  plane  geometry,  points, 
straight  lines,  and  circles.  Furthermore,  we  have  to  deal  with  certain 
relations  of  these  objects  to  one  another.  For  instance,  in  the  example 

^  Gauss,  Riemann,  Helmholtz  are  the  names  which  will  carry  perhaps  the 
greatest  weight. 

^  Cf.  La  Science  et  VHypothese.   Paris,  1903. 

^  L.  c,  chapter  v.  In  particular,  p.  93. 

<  Kempe  has  set  forth  his  ideas  in  rather  popular  form  in  the  Proceedings  of 
the  London  Mathematical  Society,  vol.  xxvi  (1894),  p.  5;  and  in  Nature,  vol.  xliii 
1890),  p.  156,  where  references  to  his  more  technical  writings  wiU  be  found. 


CONCEPTIONS   AND  METHODS   OF   MATHEMATICS    465 

just  cited;  a  given  point  may  or  may  not  lie  on  a  given  line;  a  given 
line  may  or  may  not  touch  a  given  circle;  three  or  more  points  may 
or  may  not  be  coUinear,  etc.  This  example  shows  how  in  a  single 
mathematical  problem  a  large  number  of  relations  may  be  involved, 
relations  some  of  which  connect  two  objects,  others  three,  etc. 
Moreover  these  relations  may  connect  like  or  they  may  connect 
unlike  objects;  and  finally  the  order  in  which  the  objects  are  taken 
is  not  by  any  means  immaterial  in  general,  as  is  shown  by  the  relation 
between  three  points  which  states  that  the  third  is  coUinear  v/ith  and 
lies  between  the  first  two. 

But  even  this  is  not  all;  for,  besides  these  objects  and  relations 
of  various  kinds,  we  often  have  operations  by  which  objects  can  be 
combined  to  yield  another  object,  as,  for  instance,  addition  or  multi- 
plication of  numbers.  Here  the  objects  combined  and  the  resulting 
object  are  all  of  the  same  kind,  but  this  is  by  no  means  necessary. 
We  may,  for  instance,  consider  the  operation  of  combining  two 
points  and  getting  the  perpendicular  bisector  of  the  line  connecting 
them;  or  we  may  combine  a  point  and  a  line  and  get  the  perpen- 
dicular dropped  from  the  point  on  the  line. 

These  few  examples  show  how  diverse  the  relations  and  operations, 
as  vvcll  as  the  objects  of  mathematics,  seem  at  first  sight  to  be.  Out 
of  this  apparent  diversity  it  is  not  difficult  to  obtain  a  very  great 
uniformity  by  simply  restating  the  facts  in  a  little  different  language. 
We  shall  find  it  convenient  to  indicate  that  the  objects  a,  b,  c,  .  .  .  , 
taken  in  the  order  named,  satisfy  a  relation  R  by  simply  writing 
R(a.  6,  c,  .  .  .  ),  where  it  should  be  understood  that  among  the 
objects  a,  h.  e,  .  .  .  the  same  object  may  occur  a  number  of  times. 
On  the  other  hand,  if  two  objects  a  and  h  are  combined  to  yield 
a  third  object  c,  we  may  write  a  o  b=c,^  where  the  symbol  o  is 
characteristic  of  the  special  operation  with  which  we  are  concerned. 

Lot  us  fii'st  notice  that  the  equation  aoh=c  denotes  merely 
that  the  three  objects  a,  h,  c  bear  a  certain  relation  to  one  another, 
say  R{a,  b,  c).  In  other  words  the  idea  of  an  operation  or  law  of 
combination  between  the  objects  we  deal  with,  however  convenient 
and  useful  it  ma}^  be  as  a  matter  of  notation,  is  essentially  merely 
a  way  of  expressing  the  fact  that  the  objects  combined  bear  a  certain 
relation  to  the  object  resulting  from  their  combination.  Accordingly, 
in  a  purely  abstract  discussion  like  the  present,  where  questions  of 
practical  convenience  are  not  involved,  we  need  not  consider  such 
rules  of  combination.^ 

'  I  speak  here  merely  of  dyadic  operations,  —  i.  e.,  of  operations  by  which 
two  objects  are  combined  to  yield  a  third,  —  these  being  by  far  the  most  import- 
ant as  well  as  the  simplest.  What  is  said,  however,  obviously  applies  to  opera- 
tions by  which  any  number  of  objects  are  combined. 

^  Even  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  technical  mathematician  it  may  some- 
times be  desirable  to  adopt  the  point  of  view  of  a  relation  rather  than  that  of  an 
operation.  This  is  seen,  for  instance,  in  laying  down  a  system  of  postulates  for  the 


466  MATHEMATICS 

Furthermore,  it  is  easy  to  see  that  when  we  speak  of  objects  of 
different  kinds,  as,  for  instance,  the  points  and  hnes  of  geometry,  we 
are  introducing  a  notion  which  can  very  readily  be  expressed  in  our 
relational  notation.  For  this  purpose  we  need  merely  to  introduce 
a  further  relation  which  is  satisfied  by  two  or  more  objects  when  and 
only  when  they  are  of  the  same  "kind/' 

Let  us  turn  finally  to  the  relations  themselves.  It  is  customary 
to  distinguish  here  between  dyadic  relations,  triadic  relations,  etc., 
according  as  the  relation  in  question  connects  two  objects,  three 
objects,  etc.  There  are,  however,  relations  which  may  connect  any 
number  of  objects,  as,  for  instance,  the  relation  of  collinearity  which 
may  hold  between  any  number  of  points.  Any  relation  holds  for 
certain  ordered  groups  of  objects  but  not  for  others,  and  it  is  in  no 
way  necessary  for  us  to  fix  our  attention  on  the  fact,  if  it  be  true, 
that  the  number  of  objects  in  all  the  groups  for  which  a  particular 
relation  holds  is  the  same.  This  is  the  point  of  view  we  shall  adopt, 
and  we  shall  relegate  the  property  that  a  relation  is  dyadic,  triadic, 
etc.,  to  the  background  along  with  the  various  other  properties 
relations  may  have,^  all  of  which  must  be  taken  account  of  in  the 
proper  place. 

We  are  thus  concerned  in  any  mathematical  investigation,  from 
our  present  point  of  view,  with  just  two  conceptions:  first  a  set,  or 
as  the  logicians  say,  a  class  of  objects  a,  b,  c,  .  .  .;  and  secondly  a 
class  of  relations  R,  S,  T,  .  .  .  .  We  may  suppose  these  objects 
divested  of  any  qualitative,  quantitative,  spatial,  or  other  attributes 
which  they  may  have  had,  and  regard  them  merely  as  satisfying  or  not 
satisfying  the  relations  in  question,  where,  again,  we  are  wholly 
indifferent  to  the  nature  which  these  relations  originally  had.  And 
now  we  are  in  a  position  to  state  what  I  conceive  to  be  really  the 
essential  point  in  Kempe's  definition  of  mathematics;  although  I 
have  omitted  one  of  the  points  on  which  he  insists  most  strongly,^ 
by  saying: 

If  we  have  a  certain  class  of  objects  and  a  certain  class  of  relations, 
and  if  the  only  questions  which  we  investigate  are  whether  ordered 
groups  of  these  objects  do  or  do  not  satisfy  the  relations,  the  results 
of  the  investigation  are  called  mathematics. 

theory  of  abstract  groups  (cf.,  for  example,  Huntington,  Bulletin  of  the  Ameri- 
can Mathematical  Society,  June,  1902),  where  the  postulate: 
If  a  and  b  belong  to  the  class,  a  o  b  belongs  to  the  class, 
which  in  this  form  looks  indecomposable,  immediately  breaks  up,  when  stated  in 
the  relational  form,  into  the  following  two: 

1.  If  a  and  b  belong  to  the  class,  there  exists  an  element  c  of  the  class  such  that 
R(a,  b,  c). 

2.  If  a,  b,  c,  d  belong  to  the  class,  and  if  R{a,  b,  c)  and  R{a,  b,  d),  then  c  =  d. 

^  For  instance,  the  property  of  symmetry.  A  relation  is  said  to  be  symmetrical 
if  it  holds  or  fails  to  hold  independently  of  the  order  in  which  the  objects  are  taken. 

^  Namely,  that  the  only  relation  that  need  be  considered  is  that  of  being  "in- 
distinguishable," i.  e.,  a  S3anmetrical  and  transitive  relation  between  two  groups 
of  objects. 


CONCEPTIONS  AND  METHODS   OF  MATHEMATICS    467 

It  is  convenient  to  have  a  term  to  designate  a  class  of  objects 
associated  with  a  class  of  relations  between  these  objects.  Such  an 
aggregate  we  will  speak  of  as  a  mathematical  system.  If  now  we  have 
two  different  mathematical  systems,  and  if  a  one-to-one  correspond- 
ence can  be  set  up  between  the  two  classes  of  objects,  and  also 
between  the  two  classes  of  relations  in  such  a  way  that  whenever 
a  certain  ordered  set  of  objects  of  the  first  system  satisfies  a  relation 
of  that  system,  the  set  consisting  of  the  corresponding  objects  of  the 
second  system  satisfies  the  corresponding  relation  of  that  system, 
and  vice  versa,  then  it  is  clear  that  the  two  systems  are,  from  our 
present  point  of  view,  mathematically  equivalent,  however  different 
the  nature  of  the  objects  and  relations  may  be  in  the  two  cases. ^  To 
use  a  technical  term,  the  two  systems  are  simply  isomorphic.^ 

It  will  be  noticed  that  in  the  definition  of  mathematics  just  given 
nothing  is  said  as  to  the  method  by  which  we  are  to  ascertain  whether 
or  not  a  given  relation  holds  between  the  objects  of  a  given  set.  The 
method  used  may  be  a  purely  empirical  one,  or  it  may  be  partly  or 
wholly  deductive.  Thus,  to  take  a  very  simple  case,  suppose  our  class 
of  objects  to  consist  of  a  large  number  of  points  in  a  plane  and  sup- 
pose the  only  relation  between  them  with  which  we  are  concerned 
is  that  of  collinearity.  Then,  if  the  points  are  given  us  by  being 
marked  in  ink  on  a  piece  of  white  paper,  we  can  begin  by  taking  three 
pins,  sticking  them  into  the  paper  at  three  of  the  points;  then,  by 
sighting  along  them,  we  can  determine  whether  or  not  these  points 
are  collinear.  We  can  do  the  same  with  other  groups  of  three 
points,  then  with  all  groups  of  four  points,  etc.  The  same  result 
can  be  obtained  with  much  less  labor  if  we  make  use  of  certain 
simple  properties  which  the  relation  of  collinearity  satisfies,  pro- 
perties which  are  expressed  by  such  propositions  as: 

R(a,  h,  c)  implies  RQ),  a,  c), 

R{a,  h,  c,  d)  implies  R{a,  h,  c), 

R(a,  b,  c)  and  R(a,  b,  d)  together  imply  R(a,  b,  c,  d),  etc. 

By  means  of  a  small  number  of  propositions  of  this  sort  it  is  easy 
to  show  that  no  empirical  observations  as  to  the  collinearity  of 
groups  of  more  than  three  points  need  be  made,  and  that  it  may 
not  be  necessary  to  examine  even  all  groups  of  three  points.   Having 

^  The  point  of  view  here  brought  out,  including  the  term  isomorphism,  was 
first  developed  in  a  special  case,  —  the  theory  of  groups. 

^  Inasmuch  as  the  relations  in  a  mathematical  system  are  themselves  objects, 
we  may,  if  we  choose,  take  our  class  of  objects  so  as  to  include  these  relations  as 
well  as  what  we  called  objects  before,  some  of  which,  we  may  remark  in  passing, 
may  themselves  be  relations.  Looked  at  from  this  point  of  view,  we  need  pne 
additional  relation  which  is  now  the  only  one  which  we  explicitly  eaU  a  relation. 
If  we  denote  this  relation  by  inclosing  the  objects  which  satisfy  it  in  parentheses, 
then  if  the  relation  denoted  before  by  R{a,  b)  is  satisfied,  we  should  now  write 
{R,  a,  b),  whereas  we  should  not  have  {a,  R,  b)  (S,  R,  a,  b),  etc.  Thus  we  see  that 
any  mathematical  system  may  be  regarded  as  consisting  of  a  class  of  objects  and 
a  single  relation  between  them. 


468  MATHEMATICS 

made  this  relatively  small  number  of  observations,  the  remaining 
results  would  be  obtained  deductively.  Finally,  we  may  suppose 
the  points  given  by  their  coordinates,  in  which  case  the  complete 
answer  to  our  question  may  be  obtained  by  the  purely  deductive 
method  of  analytic  geometry. 

According  to  the  modified  form  of  Kempe's  definition  which  I 
have  just  stated,  mathematics  is  not  necessarily  a  deductive  science. 
This  view,  while  not  in  accord  with  the  prevailing  ideas  of  mathe- 
maticians, undoubtedly  has  its  advantages  as  well  as  its  dangers. 
The  non-deductive  processes,  of  which  I  shall  have  more  to  say 
presently,  play  too  important  a  part  in  the  life  of  mathematics  to 
be  ignored,  and  the  definition  just  given  has  the  merit  of  not  exclud- 
ing them.  It  would  seem,  however,  that  the  definition  in  the  form 
just  given  is  too  broad.  It  would  include,  for  instance,  the  deter- 
mination by  experimental  methods  of  what  pairs  of  chemical  com- 
pounds of  the  known  elements  react  on  one  another  when  mixed 
under  given  conditions. 

VL   Axioms  and  Postulates.     Existence  Theorems 

If,  however,  we  restrict  ourselves  to  exact  or  deductive  mathe- 
matics, it  will  be  seen  that  Kempe's  definition  becomes  coextensive 
with  Peirce's.  Here,  in  order  to  have  a  starting-point  for  deductive 
reasoning,  we  must  assume  a  certain  number  of  facts  or  primitive 
propositions  concerning  any  mathematical  system  we  wish  to  study, 
of  which  all  other  propositions  will  be  necessary  consequences.^ 
We  touch  here  on  a  subject  whose  origin  goes  back  to  Euclid  and 
which  has  of  late  years  received  great  development,  primarily  at 
the  hands  of  Italian  mathematicians.^ 

It  is  important  for  us  to  notice  at  this  point  that  not  merely  these 
primitive  propositions  but  all  the  propositions  of  mathematics  may 
be  divided  into  two  great  classes.  On  the  one  hand,  we  have  pro- 
positions which  state  that  certain  specified  objects  satisfy  certain 
specified  relations.  On  the  other  hand  are  the  existence  theorems, 
which  state  that  there  exist  objects  satisfying,  along  with  certain 
specified  objects,  certain  specified  relations.^  These  two  classes  of 
propositions  are  well  known  to  logicians  and  are  designated  by  them 

^  These  primitive  propositions  may  be  spoken  of  as  axioms  or  postulates,  ac- 
cording to  the  point  of  view  we  wish  to  take  concerning  their  source,  the  word 
axiom,  which  has  been  much  misused  of  late,  indicating  an  intuitional  or  empirical 
source. 

^  Peano,  Fieri,  Padoa,  Burali-Forti.  We  may  mention  here  also  Hilbert,  who, 
apparently  without  knowing  of  the  important  work  of  his  Italian  predecessors, 
has  also  done  valuable  work  along  these  lines. 

^  Or  we  might  conceivably  have  existence  theorems  which  state  that  there 
exist  relations  which  are  satisfied  by  certain  specified  objects;  or  these  two  kinds 
of  existence  theorems  might  be  combined.  If  we  take  the  point  of  view  explained 
in  the  second  footnote  on  p.  467,  all  existence  theorems  will  be  of  the  type  men- 
tioned in  the  text. 


CONCEPTIONS   AND   METHODS   OF   MATHEMATICS    469 

universal  and  particular  propositions  respectively.^  It  is  only  during 
the  last  fifty  years  or  so  that  mathematicians  have  become  conscious 
of  the  fundamental  importance  in  their  science  of  existence  theorems, 
which  until  then  they  had  frequently  assumed  tacitly  as  they  needed 
them,  without  always  being  conscious  of  what  they  were  doing. 

It  is  sometimes  held  by  non-mathematicians  that  if  mathematics 
were  really  a  purely  deductive  science,  it  could  not  have  gained 
anything  like  the  extent  which  it  has  without  losing  itself  in  trivial- 
ities and  becoming,  as  Poincare  puts  it,  a  vast  tautology.^  This 
view  would  doubtless  be  correct  if  all  primitive  propositions  were 
universal  propositions.  One  of  the  most  characteristic  features  of 
mathematical  reasoning,  however,  is  the  use  which  it  makes  of  aux- 
iliary elements.  I  refer  to  the  auxiliary  points  and  lines  in  proofs 
by  elementary  geometry,  the  quantities  formed  by  combining  in 
various  ways  the  numbers  which  enter  into  the  theorems  to  be 
proved  in  algebra,  etc.  Without  the  use  of  such  auxiliary  elements 
mathematicians  would  be  incapable  of  advancing  a  step;  and 
whenever  we  make  use  of  such  an  element  in  a  proof,  we  are  in  reality 
using  an  existence  theorem.'  These  existence  theorems  need  not, 
to  be  sure,  be  among  the  primitive  propositions;  but  if  not,  they  must 
be  deduced  from  primitive  propositions  some  of  which  are  existence 
theorems,  for  it  is  clear  that  an  existence  theorem  cannot  be  deduced 
from  universal  propositions  alone.*  Thus  it  may  fairly  be  said  that 
existence  theorems  form  the  vital  principle  of  mathematics,  but  these 
in  turn,  it  must  be  remembered,  would  be  impotent  without  the 
material  basis  of  universal  propositions  to  work  upon. 

VII.  RusseWs  Definition 

We  have  so  far  arrived  at  the  view  that  exact  mathematics  is 
the  study  by  deductive  methods  of  what  we  have  called  a  mathe- 
matical system,  that  is,  a  class  of  objects  and  a  class  of  relations 
between  them.  If  we  elaborate  this  position  in  two  directions  we 
shall  reach  the  standpoint  of  Russell.^ 

In  the  first  place  Russell  makes  precise  the  term  deductive  method 

*  "All  men  are  mortals"  is  a  standard  example  of  a  universal  proposition; 
while  as  an  illustration  of  a  particular  proposition  is  often  given:  "Some  men  are 
Greeks."  That  this  is  really  an  existence  theorem  is  seen  more  clearly  when  we 
state  it  in  the  form:  "There  exists  at  least  one  man  who  is  a  Greek." 

^  Cf.  La  Science  et  VHypothese,  p.  10. 

'  Even  when  in  algebra  we  consider  the  sum  of  two  numbers  a  +  6,  we  are  using 
the  existence  theorem  which  says  that,  any  two  numbers  a  and  h  being  given, 
there  exists  a  number  c  which  stands  to  them  in  the  relation  which  we  indicate  in 
ordinary  language  by  saying  that  c  is  the  sum  of  a  and  b. 

*  The  power  which  resides  in  the  method  of  mathematical  induction,  so  called, 
comes  from  the  fact  that  this  method  depends  on  an  existence  theorem.  It  is, 
however,  not  the  only  fertile  principle  in  mathematics  as  Poincare  would  have 
us  believe  (cf.  La  Science  et  VHypothese).  In  fact  there  are  great  branches  of 
mathematics,  like  elementary  geometry,  in  which  it  takes  little  or  no  part. 

^  The  Principles  of  Mathematics,  Cambridge,  England,  1903. 


470  MATHEMATICS 

by  laying  down  explicitly  a  list  of  logical  conceptions  and  prin- 
ciples which  alone  are  to  be  used;  and,  secondly,  he  insists,^  on  the 
contrary,  that  no  mathematical  system,  to  use  again  the  technical 
term  introduced  above,  be  studied  in  pure  mathematics  whose  exist- 
ence cannot  be  established  solely  from  the  logical  principles  on  which 
all  mathematics  is  based.  Inasmuch  as  the  development  of  mathemat- 
ics during  the  last  fifty  years  has  shown  that  the  existence  of  most, 
if  not  all  the  mathematical  systems  which  have  proved  to  be  im- 
portant can  be  deduced  when  once  the  existence  of  positive  integers 
is  granted,  the  point  about  which  interest  must  centre  here  is  the 
proof,  which  Russell  attempts,  of  the  existence  of  this  latter  sys- 
tem.2  This  proof  will  necessarily  require  that,  among  the  logical 
principles  assumed,  existence  theorems  be  found.  Such  theorems 
do  not  seem  to  be  explicitly  stated  by  Russell,  the  existence  theorems 
which  make  their  appearance  further  on  being  evolved  out  of  some- 
what vague  philosophical  reasoning.  There  are  also  other  reasons, 
into  which  I  cannot  enter  here,  why  I  am  not  able  to  regard  the 
attempt  made  in  this  direction  by  Russell  as  completely  successful.^ 
Nevertheless,  in  view  of  the  fact  that  the  system  of  finite  positive 
integers  is  necessary  in  almost  all  branches  of  mathematics  (we 
cannot  speak  of  a  triangle  or  a  hexagon  without  having  the  numbers 
three  and  six  at  our  disposal),  it  seems  extremely  desirable  that  the 
system  of  logical  principles  which  we  lay  at  the  foundation  of  all 
mathematics  be  assumed,  if  possible,  broad  enough  so  that  the 
existence  of  positive  integers  —  at  least  finite  integers  —  follows  from 
it;  and  there  seems  little  doubt  that  this  can  be  done  in  a  satisfactory 
manner.  When  this  has  been  done  we  shall  perhaps  be  able  to  regard, 
with  Russell,  pure  mathematics  as  consisting  exclusively  of  deduc- 
tions "by  logical  principles  from  logical  principles." 

VIII.    The  Non-Deductive  Elements  in  Mathematics 

I  fear  that  many  of  you  will  think  that  what  I  have  been  saying 
is  of  an  extremely  one-sided  character,  for  I  have  insisted  merely  on 
the  rigidly  deductive  form  of  reasoning  used  and  the  purely  abstract 
character  of  the  objects  considered  in  mathematics.  These,  to  the 
great  majority  of  mathematicians,  are  only  the  dry  bones  of  the 
science.  Or,  to  change  the  simile,  it  may  perhaps  be  said  that  instead 
of  inviting  you  to  a  feast  I  have  merely  shown  you  the  empty  dishes 

'  In  the  formal  definition  of  mathematics  at  the  beginning  of  the  book  this  is 
not  stated  or  in  any  way  implied;  and  yet  it  comes  out  so  clearly  throughout 
the  book  that  this  is  a  point  of  view  which  the  author  regards  as  essential,  that 
I  have  not  hesitated  to  include  it  as  a  part  of  his  definition. 

^  Cf.  also  Burali-Forti,  Congres  internationale  de  philosophie.  Paris,  vol.  iii, 
p.  280. 

^  PLUssell's  unequivocal  repudiation  of  nominalism  in  mathematics  seems  to 
me  a  serious  if  not  an  insurmountable  barrier  to  progress. 


CONCEPTIONS  AND   METHODS   OF   MATHEMATICS    471 

and  explained  how  the  feast  would  be  served  if  only  the  dishes  were 
filled,^  I  fully  agree  with  this  opinion,  and  can  only  plead  in  excuse 
that  my  subject  was  the  fundamental  conceptions  and  methods  of 
mathematics,  not  the  infinite  variety  of  detail  and  application 
which  give  our  science  its  real  vitality.  In  fact  I  should  like  to 
subscribe  most  heartily  to  the  view  that  in  mathematics,  as  else- 
where, the  discussion  of  such  fundamental  matters  derives  its  interest 
mainly  from  the  importance  of  the  theory  of  which  they  are  the 
so-called  foundations.^  I  like  to  look  at  mathematics  almost  more 
as  an  art  than  as  a  science;  for  the  activity  of  the  mathematician, 
constantly  creating  as  he  is,  guided  though  not  controlled  by  the 
external  world  of  the  senses,  bears  a  resemblance,  not  fanciful  I 
believe  but  real,  to  the  activity  of  an  artist,  of  a  painter  let  us  say. 
Rigorous  deductive  reasoning  on  the  part  of  the  mathematician 
may  be  likened  here  to  technical  skill  in  drawing  on  the  part  of  the 
painter.  Just  as  no  one  can  become  a  good  painter  without  a  certain 
amount  of  this  skill,  so  no  one  can  become  a  mathematician  without 
the  power  to  reason  accurately  up  to  a  certain  point.  Yet  these 
qualities,  fundamental  though  they  are,  do  not  make  a  painter  or 
a  mathematician  worthy  of  the  name,  nor  indeed  are  they  the  most 
important  factors  in  the  case.  Other  qualities  of  a  far  more  subtle 
sort,  chief  among  which  in  both  cases  is  imagination,  go  to  the 
making  of  the  good  artist  or  good  mathematician.  I  must  content 
myself  merely  by  recalling  to  you  this  somewhat  vague  and  difficult 
though  interesting  field  of  speculation  which  arises  when  we  attempt 
to  attach  value  to  mathematical  work,  a  field  which  is  familiar 
enough  to  us  all  in  the  analogous  case  of  artistic  or  literary  criticism. 
We  are  in  the  habit  of  speaking  of  logical  rigor  and  the  considera- 
tion of  axioms  and  postulates  as  the  foundations  on  which  the  superb 
structure  of  modern  mathematics  rests;  and  it  is  often  a  matter  of 
wonder  how  such  a  great  edifice  can  rest  securely  on  such  a  small 
foundation.  Moreover,  these  foundations  have  not  always  seemed  so 
secure  as  they  do  at  present.  During  the  first  half  of  the  nineteenth 
century  certain  mathematicians  of  a  critical  turn  of  mind  —  Cauchy, 
Abel,  Weierstrass,  to  mention  the  greatest  of  them  —  perceived  to 
their  dismay  that  these  foundations  were  not  sound,  and  some  of  the 
best  efforts  of  their  lives  were  devoted  to  strengthening  and  improv- 
ing them.  And  yet  I  doubt  whether  the  great  results  of  mathematics 

_  •  Notice  that  just  as  the  empty  dishes  could  be  filled  by  a  great  variety  of 
viands,  so  the  empty  symbols  of  mathematics  can  be  given  meanings  of  the  most 
varied  sorts. 

^  Cf .  the  following  remark  by  Study,  JahresbericM  der  deutachcn  Mathematiker^ 
Vereinigung,  vol.  xi  (1902),  p.  313: 

"  So  wertvoll  auch  Untersuchungen  iiber  die  systematische  Stellung  der  math- 
ematischen  Grundbegriffe  sind  .  .  .  wertvoller  ist  doch  noch  der  materielle  Inhalt 
der  einzelnen  Disciplinen,  um  dessentwillen  allein  ja  derartige  Untersuchungen 
tiberhaupt  Zweck  haben,  ,  .  ," 


472  MATHEMATICS 

seemed  less  certain  to  any  of  them  because  of  the  weakness  they 
perceived  in  the  foundations  on  which  these  results  are  built  up. 
The  fact  is  that  what  we  call  mathematical  rigor  is  merely  one  of 
the  foundation  stones  of  the  science;  an  important  and  essential 
one  surely,  yet  not  the  only  thing  upon  which  we  can  rely.  A  science 
which  has  developed  along  such  broad  lines  as  mathematics,  with 
such  numerous  relations  of  its  parts  both  to  one  another  and  to  other 
sciences,  could  not  long  contain  serious  error  without  detection. 
This  explains  how,  again  and  again,  it  has  come  about,  that  the 
most  important  mathematical  developments  have  taken  place  by 
methods  which  cannot  be  wholly  justified  by  our  present  canons  of 
mathematical  rigor,  the  logical  "foundation"  having  been  supplied 
only  long  after  the  superstructure  had  been  raised.  A  discussion 
and  analysis  of  the  non-deductive  methods  which  the  creative 
mathematician  really  uses  would  be  both  interesting  and  instructive. 
Here  I  must  content  myself  with  the  enumeration  of  a  few  of  them. 

First  and  foremost  there  is  the  use  of  intuition,  whether  geometrical, 
mechanical,  or  physical.  The  great  service  which  this  method  has 
rendered  and  is  still  rendering  to  mathematics  both  pure  and  applied 
is  so  well  known  that  a  mere  mention  is  sufficient. 

Then  there  is  the  method  of  experiment;  not  merely  the  physical 
experiments  of  the  laboratory  or  the  geometrical  experiments  I 
had  occasion  to  speak  of  a  few  minutes  ago,  but  also  arithmetical 
experiments,  numerous  examples  of  which  are  found  in  the  theory 
of  numbers  and  in  analysis.  The  mathematicians  of  the  past  fre- 
quently used  this  method  in  their  printed  works.  That  this  is  now 
seldom  done  must  not  be  taken  to  indicate  that  the  method  itself  is 
not  used  as  much  as  ever. 

Closely  allied  to  this  method  of  experiment  is  the  method  of 
analogy,  which  assumes  that  something  true  of  a  considerable  num- 
ber of  cases  will  probably  be  true  in  analogous  cases.  This  is,  of 
course,  nothing  but  the  ordinary  method  of  induction.  But  in  mathe- 
matics induction  may  be  employed  not  merely  in  connection  with 
the  experimental  method,  but  also  to  extend  results  won  by  deduct- 
ive methods  to  other  analogous  cases.  This  use  of  induction  has 
often  been  unconscious  and  sometimes  overbold,  as,  for  instance, 
when  the  operations  of  ordinary  algebra  were  extended  without 
scruple  to  infinite  series. 

Finally  there  is  what  may  perhaps  be  called  the  method  of  optim- 
ism, which  leads  us  either  willfully  or  instinctively  to  shut  our  eyes 
to  the  possibility  of  evil.  Thus  the  optimist  who  treats  a  problem  in 
algebra  or  analytic  geometry  will  say,  if  he  stops  to  reflect  on  what 
he  is  doing:  ''1  know  that  I  have  no  right  to  divide  by  zero;  but 
there  are  so  many  other  values  which  the  expression  by  which  I  am 
dividing  might  have  that  I  will  assume  that  the  Evil  One  has  not 


CONCEPTIONS  AND  METHODS   OF   MATHEMATICS   473 

thrown  a  zero  in  my  denominator  this  time."  This  method,  if  a  pro- 
ceeding often  unconscious  can  be  called  a  method,  has  been  of  great 
service  in  the  rapid  development  of  many  branches  of  mathematics^ 
though  it  may  well  be  doubted  whether  in  a  subject  as  highly  devel- 
oped as  is  ordinary  algebra  it  has  not  now  survived  its  usefulness.^ 
While  no  one  of  these  methods  can  in  any  way  compare  with 
that  of  rigorous  deductive  reasoning  as  a  method  upon  which  to 
base  mathematical  results,  it  would  be  merely  shutting  one's  eyes 
to  the  facts  to  deny  them  their  place  in  the  life  of  the  mathematical 
world,  not  merely  of  the  past  but  of  to-day.  There  is  now,  and  there 
always  will  be  room  in  the  world  for  good  mathematicians  of  every 
grade  of  logical  precision.  It  is  almost  equally  important  that  the 
small  band  whose  chief  interest  lies  in  accuracy  and  rigor  should 
not  make  the  mistake  of  despising  the  broader  though  less  accurate 
work  of  the  great  mass  of  their  colleagues;  as  that  the  latter  should 
not  attempt  to  shake  themselves  wholly  free  from  the  restraint  the 
former  would  put  upon  them.  The  union  of  these  two  tendencies 
in  the  same  individuals,  as  it  was  found,  for  instance,  in  Gauss  and 
Cauchy,  seems  the  only  sure  way  of  avoiding  complete  estrangement 
between  mathematicians  of  these  two  types. 

^  Cf.  the  very  suggestive  remarks  by  Study,  Jahresbericht  d.  Deutschen  Math- 
ematiker-Vereinigung,  vol.  xi  (1902),  p.  100,  footnote,  in  which  it  is  pointed  out 
how  rigor,  in  cases  of  this  sort,  ma}'  not  merely  serve  to  increase  the  correctness  of 
the  result,  but  actually  to  suggest  new  fields  for  mathematical  investigation. 


THE  HISTORY  OF  MATHEMATICS  IN  THE  NINETEENTH 

CENTURY 

BY   PROFESSOE   JAMES    P.    PIERPONT    OF   YALE   UNIVERSITY 

The  extraordinary  development  of  mathematics  in  the  last  century- 
is  quite  unparalleled  in  the  long  history  of  this  most  ancient  of 
sciences.  Not  only  have  those  branches  of  mathematics  which  were 
taken  over  from  the  eighteenth  century  steadily  grown,  but  entirely 
new  ones  have  sprung  up  in  almost  bewildering  profusion,  and 
many  of  these  have  promptly  assumed  proportions  of  vast  extent. 

As  it  is  obviously  impossible  to  trace  in  the  short  time  allotted  to 
me  the  history  of  mathematics  in  the  nineteenth  century  even  in 
merest  outline,  I  shall  restrict  myself  to  the  consideration  of  some 
of  its  leading  theories. 

Theory  of  Functions  of  a  Complex  Variable 

Without  doubt  one  of  the  most  characteristic  features  of  mathe- 
matics in  the  last  century  is  the  systematic  and  universal  use  of  the 
complex  variable.  Most  of  its  great  theories  received  invaluable  aid 
from  it,  and  many  owe  their  very  existence  to  it.  What  would  the 
theory  of  differential  equations  or  elliptic  functions  be  to-day  without 
it,  and  is  it  probable  that  Poncelet,  Steiner,  Chasles,  and  von  Staudt 
would  have  developed  synthetic  geometry  with  such  elegance  and 
perfection  without  its  powerful  stimulus? 

The  necessities  of  elementary  algebra  kept  complex  numbers 
persistently  before  the  eyes  of  every  mathematician.  In  the  eight- 
eenth century  the  more  daring,  as  Euler  and  Lagrange,  used  them 
sparingly;  in  general  one  avoided  them  when  possible.  Three  events, 
however,  early  in  the  nineteenth  century  changed  the  attitude  of 
mathematicians  toward  this  mysterious  guest.  In  1813  Argand 
published  his  geometric  interpretation  of  complex  numbers.  In 
1824  came  the  discovery  by  Abel  of  the  imaginary  period  of  the 
elliptic  function.  Finally  Gauss  in  his  second  memoir  on  biquadratic 
residues  (1832)  proclaims  them  a  legitimate  and  necessary  element 
of  analysis. 

The  theory  of  function  of  a  complex  variable  may  be  said  to  have 
had  its  birth  when  Cauchy  discovered  his  integral  theorem 

ff(x)dx=0 

published  in  1825.  In  a  long  series  of  publications  beginning  with 
the  Cours  d' Analyse  (1821),  Cauchy  gradually  developed  his  theory 
of  functions  and  applied  it  to  problems  of  the  most  diverse  nature; 


MATHEMATICS   IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    475 

for  example,  existence  theorems  for  implicit  functions  and  the  solu- 
tions of  certain  differential  equations,  the  development  of  functions 
in  infinite  series  and  products,  and  the  periods  of  integrals  of  one 
and  many  valued  functions. 

Meanwhile  Germany  is  not  idle;  Weierstrass  and  Riemann  de- 
velop Cauchy's  theory  along  two  distinct  and  original  paths.  Weier- 
strass starts  with  an  explicit  analytical  expression,  a  power  series, 
and  defines  his  function  as  the  totality  of  its  analytical  continua- 
tions. No  appeal  is  made  to  geometric  intuition,  his  entire  theory, 
is  strictly  arithmetical.  Riemann  growing  up  under  Gauss  and 
Dirichlet  not  only  relies  largely  on  geometric  intuition,  but  he  also 
does  not  hesitate  to  impress  mathematical  physics  into  his  service. 
Two  noteworthy  features  of  his  theory  are  the  many  leaved  surfaces 
named  after  him,  and  the  extensive  use  of  conformal  representation. 

The  history  of  functions  as  first  developed  is  largely  a  theory  of 
algebraic  functions  and  their  integrals.  A  general  theory  of  func- 
tions is  only  slowly  evolved.  For  a  long  time  the  methods  of  Cauchy, 
Riemann,  and  Weierstrass  were  cultivated  along  distinct  lines  by 
their  respective  pupils.  The  schools  of  Cauchy  and  Riemann  were 
the  first  to  coalesce.  The  entire  rigor  which  has  recently  been  im- 
parted to  their  methods  has  removed  all  reason  for  founding,  as 
Weierstrass  and  his  school  have  urged,  the  theory  of  functions  on 
a  single  algorithm,  namely,  the  power  series.  We  may  therefore  say 
that  at  the  close  of  the  century  there  is  only  one  theory  of  functions 
in  which  the  ideas  of  its  three  great  creators  are  harmoniously  united. 

Let  us  note  briefly  some  of  its  lines  of  advance.  Weierstrass  early 
observed  that  an  analytic  expression  might  represent  different 
analytic  functions  in  different  regions.  Associated  with  this  is  the 
phenomenon  of  natural  boundaries.  The  question  therefore  arose. 
What  is  the  most  general  domain  of  definition  of  an  analytic  function? 
Runge  has  shown  that  any  connected  region  may  serve  this  purpose. 
An  important  line  of  investigation  relates  to  the  analytic  expression 
of  a  function  by  means  of  infinite  series,  products,  and  fractions. 
Here  may  be  mentioned  Weierstrass 's  discovery  of  prime  factors; 
the  theorems  of  Mittag-Leffler  and  Hilbert;  Poincare's  uniform- 
ization  of  algebraic  and  analytic  functions  by  means  of  a  third 
variable,  and  the  work  of  Stieljes,  Fade,  and  Van  Vleck  on  infinite 
fractions.  Since  an  analytic  function  is  determined  by  a  single 
power  series,  which  in  general  has  a  finite  circle  of  convergence,  two 
problems  present  themselves :  determine,  first,  the  singular  points  of 
the  analytic  function  so  defined,  and,  second,  an  analytic  expression 
valid  for  its  whole  domain  of  definition.  The  celebrated  memoir  of 
Hadamard  inaugurated  a  long  series  of  investigations  on  the  first 
problem;  while  Mittag-Leffler's  star  theorem  is  the  most  important 
result  yet  obtained  relating  to  the  second. 


476  MATHEMATICS 

Another  line  of  investigation  relates  to  the  work  of  Poincare, 
Borel,  Fade,  et  al.,  on  divergent  series.  It  is,  indeed,  a  strange  vicissi- 
tude of  our  science  that  these  series  which  early  in  the  century- 
were  supposed  to  be  banished  once  and  for  all  from  rigorous  mathe- 
matics should  at  its  close  be  knocking  at  the  door  for  readmission. 

Let  us  finallj^  note  an  important  series  of  memoirs  on  integral 
transcendental  functions,  beginning  with  Weierstrass,  Laguerre,  and 
Poincare. 

Algebraic  Functions  and  their  Integrals 

A  branch  of  the  theory  of  functions  has  been  developed  to  such 
an  extent  that  it  may  be  regarded  as  an  independent  theory;  we 
mean  the  theory  of  algebraic  functions  and  their  integrals.  The 
brilliant  discoveries  of  Abel  and  Jacobi  in  the  elliptic  functions  from 
1824  to  1829  prepared  the  way  for  a  similar  treatment  of  the  hyper- 
elliptic  case.  Here  a  difficulty  of  gravest  nature  was  met.  The  cor- 
responding integrals  have  2p  linearly  independent  periods;  but  as 
Jacobi  had  shown,  a  one  valued  function  having  more  than  two 
periods  admits  a  period  as  small  as  we  choose.  It  therefore  looked 
as  if  the  elliptic  functions  admitted  no  further  generalization. 
Guided  by  Abel's  theorem,  Jacobi  at  last  discovered  the  solution  to 
the  difficulty  (1832) ;  to  get  functions  analogous  to  the  elliptic  func- 
tions we  must  consider  functions  not  of  one  but  of  p  independent 
variables,  namely,  the  p  independent  integrals  of  the  first  species. 
The  great  problem  now  before  mathematicians,  known  as  Jacobi's 
Problem  of  Inversion,  was  to  extend  this  apercu  to  the  case  of  any 
algebraic  configuration  and  develop  the  consequences.  The  first  to 
take  up  this  immense  task  were  Weierstrass  and  Riemann,  whose 
results  belong  to  the  most  brilliant  achievements  of  the  century. 
Among  the  important  notions  hereby  introduced  we  note  the  fol- 
lowing: the  birational  transformation,  rank  of  an  algebraic  con- 
figuration, class  invariants,  prime  functions,  the  theta  and  multiply 
periodic  functions  in  several  variables.  Of  great  importance  is 
Riemann 's  method  of  proving  existence  theorems,  as  also  his  repre- 
sentation of  algebraic  functions  by  means  of  integrals  of  the  second 
species. 

A  new  direction  was  given  to  research  in  this  field  by  Clebsch,  who 
considered  the  fundamental  algebraic  configuration  as  defining  a 
curve.  His  aim  was  to  bring  about  a  union  of  Riemann 's  ideas  and 
the  theory  of  algebraic  curves  for  their  mutual  benefit.  Clebsch's 
labors  were  continued  by  Brill  and  Nother;  in  their  work  the  tran-* 
scendental  methods  of  Riemann  are  placed  quite  in  the  background. 
More  recently  Klein  and  his  school  have  sought  to  unite  the  tran- 
scendental methods  of  Riemann  with  the  geometric  direction  begun 
by  Clebsch,  making  systematic  use  of  homogeneous  coordinates  and 


MATHEMATICS   IN   THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY     477 

the  invariant  theory.  Noteworthy,  also,  is  his  use  of  normal  curves 
in  (p — 1)  way  space,  to  represent  the  given  algebraic  configuration. 
Dedekind  and  Weber,  Hensel  and  Landsberg,  have  made  use  of  the 
ideal  theory  with  marked  success.  Many  of  the  difficulties  of  the 
older  theory,  e.  g.,  the  resolution  of  singularities  of  the  algebraic 
configuration,  are  treated  with  a  truly  remarkable  ease  and  generality. 
In  the  theory  of  multiply  periodic  functions  and  the  general  0 
functions  we  mention,  besides  Weierstrass,  the  researches  of  Prym, 
Krazer,  Frobenius,  Poincare,  and  Wirtinger. 

Automorphic  Functions 

Closely  connected  with  the  elliptic  functions  is  a  class  of  functions 
which  has  come  into  great  prominence  in  the  last  quarter  of  a  cen- 
tury, namely,  the  elliptic  modular  and  automorphic  functions.  Let 
us  consider  first  the  modular  functions  of  which  the  modulus  k  and 
the  absolute  invariant  J  are  the  simplest  types. 

The  transformation  theory  of  Jacobi  gave  algebraic  relations  be- 
tween such  functions  in  endless  number.  Hermite,  Fuchs,  Dedekind, 
and  Schwarz  are  forerunners,  but  the  theory  of  modular  functions  as 
it  stands  to-day  is  principally  due  to  Klein  and  his  school.  Its  goal 
is  briefly  stated  thus :   Determine  all  sub-groups  of  the  linear  group 

aX-\-3 
yx  +  d 

where  a,  (3,  y,  d  are  integers  and  ao— j5;'  =  l;  determine  for  each 
such  group  associate  modular  functions  and  investigate  their  rela- 
tion to  one  another  and  especially  to  J.  Important  features  in  this 
theory  are  the  congruence  groups  of  (1);  the  fundamental  polygon 
belonging  to  a  given  sub-group,  and  its  use  as  substitute  for  a  Rie- 
mann  surface;  the  principle  of  reflection  over  a  circle,  the  modular 
forms. 

The  theory  of  automorphic  functions  is  due  to  Klein  and  Poincare. 
It  is  a  generalization  of  the  modular  functions;  the  coefficients  in 
(1)  being  any  real  or  imaginary  numbers,  with  non-vanishing  de- 
terminant, such  that  the  group  is  discontinuous.  Both  authors  have 
recourse  to  non-Euclidean  geometry  to  interpret  the  substitutions  (1). 
Their  manner  of  showing  the  existence  of  functions  belonging  to 
a  given  group  is  quite  different.  Poincare  by  a  brilliant  stroke  of 
genius  actually  writes  down  their  arithmetic  expressions  in  terms 
of  his  celebrated  0  series.  Klein  employs  the  existence  methods  of 
Riemann.  The  relation  of  automorphic  functions  to  differential 
equations  is  studied  by  Poincare  in  detail.  In  particular,  he  shows  that 
both  variables  of  a  linear  differential  equation  with  algebraic  coeffi- 
cients can  be  expressed  uniformly  by  their  means. 


478  MATHEMATICS 

Differential  Equations 

Let  us  turn  now  to  another  great  field  of  mathematical  activity, 
the  theory  of  differential  equations.  The  introduction  of  the  theory 
of  functions  has  completely  revolutionized  this  subject.  At  the 
beginning  of  the  nineteenth  century  many  important  results  had 
indeed  been  established,  particularly  by  Euler  and  Lagrange;  but 
the  methods  employed  were  artificial,  and  broad  comprehensive 
principles  were  lacking.  By  various  devices  one  tried  to  express 
the  solution  in  terms  of  the  elementary  functions  and  quadratures 
—  a  vain  attempt;  for  as  we  know  now,  the  goal  they  strove  so 
laboriously  to  reach  was  in  general  unattainable. 

A  new  epoch  began  with  Cauchy,  who  by  means  of  his  new  theory 
of  functions  first  rigorously  established  the  existence  of  the  solution 
of  certain  classes  of  equations  in  the  vicinity  of  regular  points.  He 
also  showed  that  many  of  the  properties  of  the  elliptic  functions 
might  be  deduced  directly  from  their  differential  equations.  Ere 
long,  the  problem  of  integrating  a  differential  equation  changed 
its  base.  Instead  of  seeking  to  express  its  solution  in  terms  of  the 
elementary  functions  and  quadratures,  one  asked  what  is  the  nature 
of  the  functions  defined  by  a  given  equation.  To  answer  this  ques- 
tion we  must  first  know  what  are  the  singular  points  of  the  integral 
function  and  how  does  it  behave  in  their  vicinity.  The  number  of 
memoirs  on  this  fundamental  and  often  difficult  question  is  enormous; 
but  this  is  not  strange  if  we  consider  the  great  variety  of  interesting 
and  important  classes  of  equations  which  have  to  be  studied. 

One  of  the  first  to  open  up  this  new  path  was  Fuchs,  whose  classic 
memoirs  (1866-68)  gave  the  theory  of  linear  differential  equations 
its  birth.  These  equations  enjoy  a  property  which  renders  them 
particularly  accessible,  namely,  the  absence  of  movable  singular 
points.  They  may,  however,  possess  points  of  indetermination,  to 
use  Fuchs's  terminology,  and  little  progress  has  been  made  in  this 
case.  Noteworthy  in  this  connection  is  the  introduction  by  v.  Koch 
of  infinite  determinants,  first  considered  by  our  distinguished  coun- 
tryman Hill;  also  the  use  of  divergent  series  —  that  invention  of 
the  Devil,  as  Abel  called  them  —  by  Poincare.  A  particular  class 
of  linear  differential  equations  of  great  importance  is  the  hyper- 
geometric  equation;  the  results  obtained  by  Gauss,  Kummer, 
Riemann,  and  Schwarz  relating  to  this  equation  have  had  the  great- 
est influence  on  the  development  of  the  general  theory.  The  vast 
extent  and  importance  of  the  theory  of  linear  differential  equations 
may  be  estimated  when  we  recall  that  within  its  borders  it  embraces 
not  only  almost  all  the  elementary  functions,  but  also  the  modular 
and  automorphic  functions. 

Too  important  to  pass  over  in  silence  is  the  subject  of  algebraic 


MATHEMATICS   IN  THE   NINETEENTH  CENTURY    479 

differential  equations  with  uniform  solutions.  The  brilliant  researches 
of  Poinleve  deserve  especial  mention. 

Another  field  of  great  importance,  especially  in  mathematical 
physics,  relates  to  the  determination  of  the  solution  of  differential 
equations  with  assigned  boundary  conditions.  The  literature  of  this 
subject  is  enormous;  we  may  therefore  be  pardoned  if  mention  is 
made  only  of  the  investigation  of  our  countrymen  Bocher,  Van 
Vleck,  and  Porter. 

Since  1870  the  theory  of  differential  equations  has  been  greatly 
advanced  by  Lie's  theory  of  groups.  Assuming  that  an  equation  or  a 
system  of  equations  admits  one  or  more  infinitesimal  transformations, 
Lie  has  shown  how  they  may  be  employed  to  simplify  the  problem 
of  integration.  In  many  cases  they  give  us  exact  information  how 
to  conduct  the  solution  and  upon  what  system  of  auxiliary  equations 
the  solution  depends.  One  of  the  most  striking  illustrations  of  this 
is  the  theory  of  ordinary  linear  differential  equations  which  Picard 
and  Vessiot  have  developed,  analogous  to  Galois's  theory  for  algebraic 
equations.  An  interesting  result  of  this  theory  is  a  criterion  for  the 
solution  of  such  equations  by  quadratures.  As  an  application,  we 
find  that  Ricatti's  equation  cannot  be  solved  by  quadratures.  The 
attempts  to  effect  such  a  solution  of  this  celebrated  equation  in  the 
century  before  were  therefore  necessarily  in  vain. 

A  characteristic  feature  of  Lie's  theories  is  the  prominence  given 
to  the  geometrical  aspects  of  the  questions  involved.  Lie  thinks  in 
geometrical  images,  the  analytical  formulation  comes  afterwards. 
Already  Morge  had  shown  how  much  might  be  gained  in  geometrizing 
the  problem  of  integration.  Lie  has  gone  much  farther  in  this  direc- 
tion. Besides  employing  all  the  geometrical  notions  of  his  predeces- 
sors extended  to  7i-way  space,  he  has  introduced  a  variety  of  new 
conceptions,  chief  of  which  are  his  surface  element  and  contact 
transformations. 

He  has  also  used  with  great  effect  Pliicker's  line  geometry,  and  his 
own  sphere  geometry  in  the  study  of  certain  types  of  partial  differential 
equations  of  the  first  and  second  orders  which  are  of  great  geometrical 
interest,  for  example,  equations  whose  characteristic  curves  are  lines 
of  curvature,  geodesies,  etc.  Let  us  close  by  remarking  that  Lie's 
theories  not  only  afford  new  and  valuable  points  of  view  for  attack- 
ing old  problems,  but  also  give  rise  to  a  host  of  new  ones  of  great 
interest  and  importance. 

Groups 

We  turn  now  to  the  second  dominant  idea  of  the  century,  the 
group  concept. 

Groups  first  became  objects  of  study  in  algebra  when  Lagrange 
(1770),  Ruffini  (1799),  and  Abel  (1826)  employed  substitution  groups 


480  MATHEMATICS 

with  great  advantage  in  their  work  on  the  quintic.  The  enormous 
importance  of  groups  in  algebra  was,  however,  first  made  clear  by 
Galois,  whose  theory  of  the  solution  of  algebraic  equations  is  one 
of  the  great  achievements  of  the  century.  Its  influence  has  stretched 
far  beyond  the  narrow  bounds  of  algebra. 

With  an  arbitrary  but  fixed  domain  of  rationality,  Galois  observed 
that  every  algebraic  equation  has  attached  to  it  a  certain  group  of 
substitutions.  The  nature  of  the  auxiliary  equations  required  to 
solve  the  given  equation  is  completely  revealed  by  an  inspection  of 
this  group. 

Galois's  theory  showed  the  importance  of  determining  the  sub- 
groups of  a  given  substitution  group,  and  this  problem  was  studied 
by  Cauchy,  Serret,  Matthieu,  Kirkmann,  and  others.  The  publica- 
tion of  Jordan's  great  treatise  in  1870  is  a  noteworthy  event.  It 
collects  and  unifies  the  results  of  his  predecessors  and  contains  an 
immense  amount  of  new  matter. 

A  new  direction  was  given  to  the  theory  of  groups  by  the  introduc- 
tion by  Cayley  of  abstract  groups  (1854,  1878).  The  work  of  Sylow, 
Hdlder  and  Frobenius,  Burnside  and  Miller,  deserve  especial  notice. 

Another  line  of  research  relates  to  the  determination  of  the  finite 
groups  in  the  linear  group  of  any  number  of  variables.  These  groups 
are  important  in  the  theory  of  linear  differential  equations  with 
algebraic  solutions,  in  the  study  of  certain  geometrical  problems 
as  the  points  of  inflection  of  a  cubic,  the  twenty-seven  lines  on  a 
surface  of  the  third  order,  in  crystallography,  etc.  They  also  enter 
prominently  into  Klein's  Formen-problem.  An  especially  important 
class  of  finite  linear  groups  are  the  congruence  groups  first  considered 
by  Galois.  Among  the  laborers  in  the  field  of  linear  groups,  we  note 
Jordan,  Klein,  Moore,  Maschke,  Dickson,  Frobenius,  and  Wiman. 

Up  to  the  present  we  have  considered  only  groups  of  finite  order. 
About  1870  entirely  new  ideas  coming  from  geometry  and  differential 
equations  give  the  theory  of  groups  an  unexpected  development. 
Foremost  in  this  field  are  Lie  and  Klein. 

Lie  discovers  and  gradually  perfects  his  theory  of  continuous 
transformation  groups  and  shows  their  relations  to  many  different 
branches  of  mathematics.  In  1872  Klein  publishes  his  Erlanger 
Programme  and  in  1877  begins  his  investigations  on  elliptic  modular 
functions,  in  which  infinite  discontinuous  groups  are  of  primary  im- 
portance, as  we  have  already  seen.  In  the  now  famous  Programme, 
Klein  asks  what  is  the  principle  which  underlies  and  unifies  the 
heterogeneous  geometrical  methods  then  in  vogue,  as,  for  example, 
the  geometry  of  the  ancients,  whose  figures  are  rigid  and  invariable; 
the  modern  projective  geometry,  whose  figures  are  in  ceaseless 
flux  passing  from  one  form  to  another;  the  geometries  of  Plucker 
and  Lie,  in  which  the  elements  of  space  are  no  longer  points,  but  line 


MATHEMATICS  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY    481 

spheres,  or  other  configurations  at  pleasure,  the  geometry  of  birational 
transformation,  the  analysis  situs,  etc.,  etc.  Klein  finds  this  answer: 
In  each  geometry  we  have  a  system  of  objects  and  a  group  which 
transforms  these  objects  one  into  another.  We  seek  the  invariants 
of  this  group.  In  each  case  it  is  the  abstract  group  and  not  the  con- 
crete objects  which  is  essential.  The  fundamental  role  of  a  group  in 
geometrical  research  is  thus  made  obvious.  Its  importance  is  the 
solution  of  algebraic  equation,  in  the  theory  of  differential  equations 
in  the  automorphic  functions  we  have  already  seen.  The  immense 
theory  of  algebraic  invariants  developed  by  Cayley  and  Sylvester, 
Aronhold,  Clebsch,  Gordan,  Hermite,  Brioschi,  and  a  host  of  zealous 
workers  in  the  middle  of  the  century,  also  finds  its  place  in  the  far 
more  general  invariant  theory  of  Lie's  theory  of  groups.  The  same  is 
true  of  the  theory  of  surfaces,  so  far  as  it  rests  on  the  theory  of  differ- 
ential forms.  In  the  theory  of  numbers,  groups  have  many  important 
applications,  for  example,  in  the  composition  of  quadratic  forms  and 
the  cyclotomic  bodies.  Finally,  let  us  note  the  relation  between  hyper- 
complex  numbers  and  continuous  groups  discovered  by  Poincare. 

In  r^sum^,  we  may  thus  saj'^  that  the  group  concept,  hardly  not- 
iceable at  the  beginning  of  the  century,  has  at  its  close  become  one 
of  the  fundamental  and  most  fruitful  notions  in  the  whole  range  of 
our  science. 

Infinite  Aggregates 

Leaving  the  subject  of  groups,  we  consider  now  briefly  another 
fundamental  concept,  namely,  infinite  aggregates.  In  the  most 
diverse  mathematical  investigations  we  are  confronted  with  such 
aggregates.  In  geometry  the  conceptions  of  curves,  surface,  region, 
frontier,  etc.,  when  examined  carefully,  lead  us  to  a  rich  variety  of 
aggregates.  In  analysis  they  also  appear,  for  example,  the  domain 
of  definition  of  an  analytic  function,  the  points  where  a  function  of 
a  real  variable  ceases  to  be  continuous  or  to  have  a  differential  coeffi- 
cient, the  points  where  a  series  of  functions  ceases  to  be  uniformly 
convergent,  etc. 

To  say  an  aggregate  (not  necessarily  a  point  aggregate)  is  infinite 
is  often  an  important  step;  but  often  again  only  the  first  step.  To 
penetrate  farther  into  the  problem  may  require  us  to  state  how 
infinite.  This  requires  us  to  make  distinctions  in  infinite  aggregates, 
to  discover  fruitful  principles  of  classification,  and  to  investigate  the 
properties  of  such  classes. 

The  honor  of  having  done  this  belongs  to  George  Cantor.  The 
theory  of  aggregates  is  for  the  most  part  his  creation;  it  has  en- 
riched mathematical  science  with  fundamental  and  far-reaching 
notions  and  results. 

The  theory  falls  into  two  parts;  a  theory  of  aggregates  in  general, 


482  MATHEMATICS 

and  a  theory  of  point  aggregates.  In  the  theory  of  point  aggregates 
the  notion  of  limiting  points  gives  rise  to  important  classes  of  aggre- 
gates as  discrete,  dense,  everywhere  dense,  complete,  perfect,  con- 
nected, etc.,  which  are  so  important  in  the  function  theory. 

In  the  general  theory  two  notions  are  especially  important, 
namely,  the  one  to  one  correspondence  of  the  elements  of  two  ag- 
gregates, and  well-ordered  aggregates.  The  first  leads  to  cardinal 
numbers  and  the  idea  of  enumerable  aggregates,  the  second  to  trans- 
finite  or  ordinal  numbers. 

Two  striking  results  of  Cantor's  theory  are  these:  the  algebraic 
and  therefore  the  rational  numbers,  although  everywhere  dense,  are 
enumerable;  and  secondly,  one-way  and  n-way  space  have  the 
same  cardinal  number. 

Cantor's  theory  has  already  found  many  applications,  especially 
in  the  function  theory,  where  it  is  to-day  an  indispensable  instrument 
of  research. 

Functions  of  Real  Variables — The  Critical  Movement 

One  of  the  most  conspicuous  and  distinctive  features  of  mathe- 
matical thought  in  the  nineteenth  century  is  its  critical  spirit.  Be- 
ginning with  the  calculus,  it  soon  permeates  all  analysis,  and  toward 
the  close  of  the  century  it  overhauls  and  recasts  the  foundation  of 
geometry  and  aspires  to  further  conquests  in  mechanics  and  in  the 
immense  domains  of  mathematical  physics. 

Ushered  in  with  Lagrange  and  Gauss  just  at  the  close  of  the 
eighteenth  century,  the  critical  movement  receives  its  first  decisive 
impulse  from  the  teachings  of  Cauchy,  who  in  particular  introduces 
our  modern  definition  of  limit  and  makes  it  the  foundation  of  the 
calculus.  We  must  also  mention  in  this  connection  Abel,  Bolzano, 
and  Dirichlet.  Especially  Abel  adopted  the  reform  ideas  of  Cauchy 
with  enthusiasm,  and  made  important  contributions  in  infinite  series. 

The  figure,  however,  which  towers  above  all  others  in  this  move- 
ment, whose  name  has  become  an  epithet  of  rigor,  is  Weierstrass. 
Beginning  at  the  very  foundations,  he  creates  an  arithmetic  of  real 
and  complex  numbers,  assuming  the  theory  of  positive  integers  to  be 
given.  The  necessity  of  this  is  manifest  when  we  recall  that  until 
then  the  simplest  properties  of  radicals  and  logarithms  were  utterly 
devoid  of  a  rigorous  foundation;    so,  for  example, 

V2  \/5=\/l0  log  2+log  5=log  10 

Characteristic  of  the  pre-Weierstrassean  era  is  the  loose  way  in 
which  geometrical  and  other  intuitional  ideas  were  employed  in 
the  demonstration  of  analytical  theorems.  Even  Gauss  is  open  to 
this  criticism.  The  mathematical  world  received  a  great  shock 
when  Weierstrass  showed  them  an  example  of  a  continuous  function 


MATHEMATICS   IN  THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY    483 

without  a  derivative,  and  Hankel  and  Cantor,  by  means  of  their 
principle  of  condensation  of  singularities,  could  construct  analytic 
expressions  for  functions  having  in  any  interval  however  small  an 
infinity  of  points  of  oscillation,  an  infinity  of  points  in  which  the 
differential  coefficient  is  altogether  indeterminate,  or  an  infinity  of 
points  of  discontinuity.  Another  rude  surprise  was  Cantor's  dis- 
covery of  the  one  to  one  correspondence  between  the  points  of  a 
unit  segment  and  a  unit  square,  followed  up  by  Peano's  example 
of  a  space-filling  curve. 

These  examples  and  many  others  made  it  very  clear  that  the 
ideas  of  a  curve,  a  surface  region,  motion,  etc.,  instead  of  being  clear 
and  simple,  were  extremely  vague  and  complex.  Until  these  notions 
had  been  cleared  up,  their  admission  in  the  demonstration  of  an 
analytical  theorem  was  therefore  not  to  be  tolerated.  On  a  purely 
arithmetical  basis,  with  no  appeal  to  our  intuition,  Weierstrass 
develops  his  stately  theory  of  functions  which  culminates  in  the 
theory  of  Abelian  and  multiply  periodic  functions. 

But  the  notion  of  rigor  is  relative  and  depends  on  what  we  are 
willing  to  admit  either  tacitly  or  explicitly.  As  we  observed,  Gauss, 
whose  rigor  was  the  admiration  of  his  contemporaries,  freely  ad- 
mitted geometrical  notions.  This  Weierstrass  would  criticise.  On 
the  other  hand,  Weierstrass  has  made  a  grave  oversight:  he  no- 
where shows  that  his  definitions  relative  to  the  number  he  introduces 
do  not  involve  mutual  contradictions.  If  he  replied  that  such  con- 
tradictions would  involve  contradictions  in  the  theory  of  positive 
integers,  one  might  ask  what  assurance  have  we  that  such  contradic- 
tions may  not  actually  exist.  A  flourishing  young  school  of  mathe- 
matical logic  has  recently  grown  up  under  the  influence  of  Peano. 
They  have  investigated  with  marked  success  the  foundations  of 
analysis  and  geometry,  and  in  particular  have  attempted  to  show 
the  non-contradictoriness  of  the  axioms  of  our  number-system  by 
making  them  depend  on  the  axioms  of  logic,  which  axioms  we  must 
admit,  to  reason  at  all. 

The  critical  spirit,  which  in  the  first  half  of  the  century  was  to 
be  found  in  the  writings  of  only  a  few  of  the  foremost  mathematicians, 
has  in  the  last  quarter  of  the  century  become  almost  universal,  at 
least  in  analysis.  A  searching  examination  of  the  foundation  of 
arithmetic  and  the  calculus  has  brought  to  light  the  insufficiency  of 
much  of  the  reasoning  formerly  considered  as  conclusive.  It  became 
necessary  to  build  up  these  subjects  anew.  The  theory  of  irrational 
numbers  invented  by  Weierstrass  has  been  supplanted  by  the  more 
flexible  theories  of  Dedekind  and  Cantor.  Stolz  has  given  us  a  sys- 
tematic and  rigorous  treatment  of  arithmetic.  The  calculus  has 
been  completely  overhauled  and  arithmetized  by  Thomae,  Hamack, 
Peano,  Stolz,  Jordan,  and  Vallee-Poussin. 


484  MATHEMATICS 

Leaving  the  calculus,  let  us  notice  briefly  the  theory  of  functions 
of  real  variables.  The  line  of  demarcation  between  these  two  sub- 
jects is  extremely  arbitrary.  We  might  properly  place  in  the  latter 
all  those  finer  and  deeper  questions  relating  to  the  number-system; 
the  study  of  our  curve,  surface,  and  other  geometrical  notions,  the 
peculiarities  that  functions  present  with  reference  to  discontinuity, 
oscillation,  differentiation,  and  integration;  as  well  as  a  very  exten- 
sive class  of  investigations  whose  object  is  the  greatest  possible 
extension  of  the  processes,  concepts,  and  results  of  the  calculus. 
Among  the  many  not  yet  mentioned  who  have  made  important 
contributions  to  this  subject  we  note:  Fourier,  Riemann,  Stokes, 
Dini,  Tannery,  Pringsheim,  Arzela,  Osgood,  Broden,  Ascoli,  Borel, 
Baire,  Kopke,  Holder,  Volterra,  and  Lebesgue. 

Closely  related  with  the  differential  calculus  is  the  calculus  of 
variations;  in  the  former  the  variables  are  given  infinitesimal  varia- 
tions, in  the  latter  the  functions.  Developed  in  a  purely  formal 
manner  by  Jacobi,  Hamilton,  Clebsch,  and  others  in  the  first  part 
of  the  century,  a  new  epoch  began  with  Weierstrass,  who,  having 
subjected  the  labors  of  his  predecessors  to  an  annihilating  criticism, 
placed  the  theory  on  a  new  and  secure  foundation  and  so  opened  the 
path  for  further  research  by  Schwarz,  A.  Mayer,  Scheffers,  v,  Esche- 
rich,  Kneser,  Osgood,  Bolza,  Kobb,  Zermelo,  and  others.  At  the 
very  close  of  the  century  Hilbert  has  given  the  theory  a  fresh  im- 
pulse by  the  introduction  of  new  and  powerful  methods,  which 
enable  us  in  certain  cases  to  neglect  the  second  variation  and  sim- 
plifies the  consideration  of  the  first.  As  application  he  gives  the 
first  direct  and  yet  simple  demonstration  of  Dirichlet's  celebrated 
Principle. 

Theory  of  Numbers  —  Algebraic  Bodies 

The  theory  of  numbers  as  left  by  Fermat,  Euler,  and  Legendre 
was  for  the  most  part  concerned  with  the  solution  of  Diophantine 
equations,  that  is,  given  an  equation  f(x,  y,z,  .  .  .  )  =0  whose 
coefficients  are  integers,  find  all  rational,  and  especially  all  integral 
solutions.  In  this  problem  Lagrange  had  shown  the  importance 
of  considering  the  theory  of  forms.  A  new  era  begins  with  the  ap- 
pearance of  Gauss's  Disquisitiones  arithmeticae  in  1801.  This  great 
work  is  remarkable  for  three  things:  (1)  The  notion  of  divisibility 
in  the  form  of  congruences  is  shown  to  be  an  instrument  of  wonder- 
ful power;  (2)  the  Diophantine  problem  is  thrown  in  the  back- 
ground and  the  theory  of  forms  is  given  a  dominant  role;  (3)  the 
introduction  of  algebraic  numbers,  namely,  the  roots  of  unity. 

The  theory  of  formes  has  been  further  developed  along  the  lines 
of  the  Disquisitiones  by  Dirichlet,  Eisenstein,  Hermite,  H.  Smith,  and 
Minkowski, 


MATHEMATICS  IN  THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY    485 

Another  part  of  the  theory  of  numbers  also  goes  back  to  Gauss, 
namely,  algebraic  numerical  bodies.  The  Law  of  Reciprocity  of 
Quadratic  Residues,  one  of  the  gems  of  the  higher  arithmetic,  was 
first  rigorously  proved  by  Gauss.  His  attempts  to  extend  this 
theorem  to  cubic  and  biquadratic  residues  showed  that  the  elegant 
simplicity  which  prevailed  in  quadratic  residues  was  altogether 
missing  in  these  higher  residues,  until  one  passed  from  the  domain 
of  real  integers  to  the  domain  formed  of  the  third  and  fourth  roots  of 
unit3^  In  these  domains,  as  Gauss  remarked,  algebraic  integers  have 
essentially  the  same  properties  as  ordinary  integers.  Further  explor- 
ation in  this  new  and  promising  field  by  Jacobi,  Eisenstein,  and 
others  soon  brought  to  light  the  fact  that  already  in  the  domain 
formed  of  the  twenty-third  roots  of  unity  the  laws  of  divisibility  were 
altogether  different  from  those  of  ordinary  integers;  in  particular, 
a  number  could  be  expressed  as  the  product  of  prime  factors  in  more 
than  one  way.  Further  progress  in  this  direction  was  therefore 
apparently  impossible. 

It  is  Kummer's  immortal  achievement  to  make  further  progress 
possible  by  the  invention  of  his  ideals.  These  he  applied  to  Fermat's 
celebrated  Last  Theorem  and  the  Law  of  Reciprocity  of  Higher 
Residues. 

The  next  step  in  this  direction  was  taken  by  Dedekind  and  Kro- 
necker,  who  developed  the  ideal  theory  for  any  algebraic  domain. 
So  arose  the  theory  of  algebraic  numerical  bodies,  which  has  come 
into  such  prominence  in  the  last  decades  of  the  century  through 
the  researches  of  Hensel,  Hurwitz,  Minkowski,  Weber,  and,  above 
all,  Hilbert. 

Kronecker  has  gone  farther,  and  in  his  classic  Grundzuge  he  has 
shown  that  similar  ideas  and  methods  enable  us  to  develop  a  theory 
of  algebraic  bodies  in  any  number  of  variables.  The  notion  of  divis- 
ibility so  important  in  the  preceding  theories  is  generalized  by  Kro- 
necker still  farther  in  the  shape  of  his  system  of  moduli. 

Another  noteworthy  field  of  research  opened  up  by  Kronecker  is 
the  relation  between  quadratic  forms  with  negative  determinant 
and  complex  multiplication  of  elliptic  functions.  H.  Smith,  Gierster, 
Hurwitz,  and  especially  Weber  have  made  important  contributions. 
A  method  of  great  power  in  certain  investigations  has  been  created 
by  Minkowski,  which  he  called  the  Geometrie  der  Zahlen.  Introduc- 
ing a  generalization  of  the  distance  function,  he  is  led  to  the  concep- 
tion of  a  fundamental  body  (Aichkorper) .  Minkowski  shows  that 
every  fundamental  body  is  nowhere  concave,  and  conversely  to 
each  such  body  belongs  a  distance  function.  A  theorem  of  great 
importance  is  now  the  following:  The  minimum  value  which  each 
distance  function  has  at  the  lattice  points  is  not  greater  than  a  certain 
number  depending  on  the  function  chosen. 


486  MATHEMATICS 

We  wish  finally  to  mention  a  line  of  investigation  which  makes 
use  of  the  infinitesimal  calculus  and  even  the  theory  of  functions. 
Here  belong  the  brilliant  researches  of  Dirichlet  relating  to  the  num- 
ber of  classes  of  binary  forms  for  a  given  determinant,  the  number 
of  primes  in  a  given  arithmetic  progression;  and  Riemann's  remark- 
able memoir  on  the  number  of  primes  in  a  given  interval. 

In  this  analytical  side  of  the  theory  of  numbers  we  notice  also  the 
researches  of  Mertens,  Weber,  and  Hadamard. 

Projective  Geometry 

The  tendencies  of  the  eighteenth  century  were  predominantly 
analytical.  Mathematicians  were  absorbed  for  the  most  part  in 
developing  the  wonderful  instrument  of  the  calculus  with  its  countless 
applications.  Geometry  made  relatively  little  progress.  A  new  era 
begins  with  Monge.  His  numerous  and  valuable  contributions  to 
analytical  descriptive  and  differential  geometry,  and  especially  his 
brilliant  and  inspiring  lectures  at  the  Ecole  Polytechnique  (1795, 
1809),  put  fresh  life  into  geometry  and  prepared  it  for  a  new  and 
glorious  development  in  the  nineteenth  century. 

When  one  passes  in  review  the  great  achievements  which  have 
made  the  nineteenth  century  memorable  in  the  annals  of  our  science, 
certainly  projective  geometry  will  occupy  a  foremost  place.  Pascal, 
De  la  Hire,  Monge,  and  Carnot  are  forerunners,  but  Poncelet,  a  pupil 
of  Monge,  is  its  real  creator.  The  appearance  of  his  Traite  des  pro- 
prietes  projectives  des  figures,  in  1822,  gives  modern  geometry  its 
birth.  In  it  we  find  the  line  at  infinity,  the  introduction  of  imagin- 
aries,  the  circular  points  at  infinity,  polar  reciprocation,  a  discus- 
sion of  homology,  the  systematic  use  of  projection,  section,  and 
anharmonic  ratio. 

While  the  countrymen  of  Poncelet,  especially  Chasles,  do  not  fail 
to  make  numerous  and  valuable  contributions  to  the  new  geometry, 
the  next  great  steps  in  advance  are  made  on  German  soil.  In  1827 
Mobius  publishes  the  Barycentrische  Calcul;  Pliicker's  Analytisch- 
geometrische  Entioickelungen  appears  in  1828-31  and  Steiner's  Ent- 
ivickelung  der  Abhdngigkeit  geometrischer  Gestalten  von  einander  in 
1832.  In  the  ten  years  which  embrace  the  publication  of  these 
immortal  works  of  Poncelet,  Pliicker,  and  Steiner,  geometry  has 
made  more  real  progress  than  in  the  two  thousand  years  which  had 
elapsed  since  the  time  of  Appolonius.  The  ideas  which  had  been 
slowly  taking  shape  since  the  time  of  Descartes  suddenly  crystallized 
and  almost  overwhelmed  geometry  with  an  abundance  of  new  ideas 
and  principles. 

To  Mobius  we  owe  the  introduction  of  homogeneous  coordinates, 
and  the  far-reaching  conception  of  geometric  transformation,  includ- 
ing collineation  and  duality  as  special  cases.   To  Pliicker  we  owe  the 


MATHEMATICS   IN   THE   NINETEENTH  CENTURY    487 

use  of  the  abbreviate  notation  which  permits  us  to  study  the  proper- 
ties of  geometric  figures  without  the  intei'vention  of  the  coordinates, 
the  introduction  of  Une  and  plane  coordinates,  and  the  notion  of 
generahzed  space  elements.  Steiner,  who  has  been  called  the  greatest 
geometer  since  Appolonius,  besides  enriching  geometry  in  countless 
ways,  was  the  first  to  employ  systematically  the  method  of  generating 
geometrical  figures  by  means  of  projective  pencils. 

Other  noteworthy  works  belonging  to  this  period  are  Pliicker's 
System  der  analytischen  Geometrie  (1835),  and  Chasles's  classic  Apercu 
(1837). 

Already  at  this  stage  we  notice  a  bifurcation  in  geometrical 
methods.  Steiner  and  Chasles  become  eloquent  champions  of  the 
synthetic  school  of  geometry,  while  Pliicker,  and  later  Hesse  and 
Cayley,  are  leaders  in  the  analytical  movement.  The  astonishing 
fruitfulness  and  beauty  of  synthetic  methods  threatened  for  a  short 
time  to  drive  the  analytic  school  out  of  existence.  The  tendency 
of  the  synthetic  school  was  to  banish  more  and  more  metrical  methods. 
In  effecting  this  the  anharmonic  ratio  became  constantly  more  promi- 
nent. To  define  this  fundamental  ratio  mthout  reference  to  measure- 
ment, and  so  free  projective  geometry  from  the  galling  bondage 
of  metric  relations,  was  thus  a  problem  of  fundamental  importance. 
The  glory  of  this  achievement,  which  has,  as  we  shall  see,  a  far 
wider  significance,  belongs  to  v.  Staudt.  Another  equally  important 
contribution  of  v.  Staudt  to  synthetic  geometry  is  his  theory  of 
imaginaries.  Poncelet,  Steiner,  Chasles  operate  with  imaginary 
elements  as  if  they  were  real.  Their  only  justification  is  recourse  to 
the  so-called  principles  of  continuity  or  to  some  other  equally  vague 
principle.  V.  Staudt  gives  this  theory  a  rigorous  foundation,  defining 
the  imaginary  points,  lines,  and  planes  by  means  of  involutions 
without  ordinal  elements. 

The  next  great  advance  made  is  the  advent  of  the  theory  of  alge- 
braic invariants.  Since  projective  geometry  is  the  study  of  those 
properties  of  geometric  figures  which  remain  unaltered  by  projective 
transformations,  and  since  the  theory  of  invariants  is  the  study  of 
those  forms  which  remain  unaltered  (except  possibly  for  a  numerical 
factor)  by  the  group  of  linear  substitutions,  these  two  subjects  are 
inseparably  related  and  in  many  respects  only  different  aspects  of  the 
same  thing.  It  is  no  wonder,  then,  that  geometers  speedily  applied 
the  new  theory  of  invariants  to  geometrical  problems.  Among  the 
pioneers  in  this  direction  were  Cayley,  Salmon,  Aronhold,  Hesse, 
and  especially  Clebsch. 

Finally  we  must  mention  the  introduction  of  the  line  as  a  space 
element.  Forerunners  are  Grassmann  (1844)  and  Cayley  (1859),  but 
Pliicker  in  his  memoirs  of  1865,  and  his  work  Neue  Geometrie  des 
Raumes  (1868-69),  was  the  first  to  show  its  great  value  by  studying 


488  MATHEMATICS 

complexes  of  the  first  and  second  order  and  calling  attention    to 
their  application  to  mechanics  and  optics. 

The  most  important  advance  over  Pliicker  has  been  made  by- 
Klein,  who  takes  as  coordinates  six-line  complexes  in  involution. 
Klein  also  observed  that  line  geometry  may  be  regarded  as  a  point 
geometry  on  a  quadric  in  five-way  space.  Other  laborers  in  this 
field  are  Clebsch,  Reye,  Segre,  Sturm,  and  Konigs. 

Differential  Geometry 

During  the  first  quarter  of  the  century  this  important  branch  of 
geometry  was  cultivated  chiefly  by  the  French.  Monge  and  his 
school  study  with  great  success  the  generation  of  surfaces  in  vari- 
ous wayS;  the  properties  of  envelopes,  evolutes,  lines  of  curvature, 
asymptotic  lines,  skew  curves,  orthogonal  systems,  and  especially  the 
relation  between  the  surface  theory  and  partial  differential  equations. 

The  appearance  of  Gauss's  Disquisitiones  generates  circa  super- 
ficies curvas,  in  1828,  marks  a  new  epoch.  Its  wealth  of  new  ideas 
has  furnished  material  for  countless  memoirs,  and  given  geometry 
a  new  direction.  We  find  here  the  parametric  representation  of  a 
surface,  the  introduction  of  curvilinear  coordinates,  the  notion  of 
spherical  image,  the  Gaussian  measure  of  curvature,  and  a  study  of 
geodesies.  But  by  far  the  most  important  contributions  that  Gauss 
makes  in  this  work  is  the  consideration  of  a  surface  as  a  flexible, 
inextensible  film  or  membrane,  and  the  importance  given  quadratic 
differential  forms. 

We  consider  now  some  of  the  lines  along  which  differential  geometry 
has  advanced.  The  most  important  is  perhaps  the  theory  of  differen- 
tial quadratic  forms  with  their  associate  invariants  and  parameters. 
We  mention  here  Lame,  Beltrami,  Menardi,  Codazzi,  Christoffel, 
and  Weingarten. 

An  especially  beautiful  application  of  this  theory  is  the  immense 
subject  of  applicability  and  deformation  of  surfaces,  in  which  Mind- 
ing, Bauer,  Beltrami,  Weingarten,  and  Voss  have  made  important 
contributions. 

Intimately  related  with  the  theory  of  applicability  of  two  surfaces 
is  the  theory  of  surfaces  of  constant  curvature  which  play  so  import- 
ant a  part  in  non-Euclidean  geometry.  We  mention  here  the  work 
of  Minding,  Beltrami,  Dini,  Backlund,  and  Lie. 

The  theory  of  rectilinear  congruences  has  also  been  the  subject 
of  important  researches  from  the  standpoint  of  differential  geometry. 
First  studied  by  Monge  as  a  sj^stem  of  normals  to  a  surface  and  then 
in  connection  with  optics  by  Malus,  Dupin,  and  Hamilton,  the  gen- 
eral theory  has  since  been  developed  by  Kummer,  Ribaucour, 
Guichard,  Darboux,  Voss,  and  Weingarten.  An  important  applica- 
tion of  this  theory  is  the  infinitesimal  deformation  of  a  surface. 


MATHEMATICS   IN  THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY     489 

Minimum  surfaces  have  been  studied  by  Monge,  Bonnet,  and 
Enneper.  The  subject  owes  its  present  extensive  development  prin- 
cipally to  Weierstrass,  Riemann,  Schwarz,  and  Lie.  In  it  we  find 
harmoniously  united  the  theory  of  surfaces,  the  theory  of  functions, 
the  calculus  of  variations,  the  theory  of  groups,  and  mathematical 
physics. 

Another  extensive  division  of  differential  geometry  is  the  theory  of 
orthogonal  systems,  of  such  importance  in  physics.  We  note  espe- 
cially the  investigations  of  Dupin,  jacobi,  Darboux,  Combescure, 
and  Bianchi. 

Other  Branches  of  Geometry 

Under  this  head  we  group  a  number  of  subjects  too  important 
to  pass  over  in  silence,  3^et  which  cannot  be  considered  at  length  for 
lack  of  time. 

In  the  first  place  is  the  immense  subject  of  algebraic  curves  and 
surfaces.  To  develop  adequately  all  the  important  and  elegant 
properties  of  curves  and  surfaces  of  the  second  order  alone  would 
require  a  bulky  volume.  In  this  line  of  ideas  would  follow  curves 
and  surfaces  of  higher  order  and  class.  Their  theory  is  far  less 
complete,  but  this  lack  it  amply  makes  good  by  offering  an  almost 
bewildering  variety  of  configurations  to  classify  and  explore.  No 
single  geometer  has  contributed  more  to  this  subject  than  Cayley. 

A  theory  of  great  importance  is  the  geometry  on  a  curve  or  sur- 
face inaugurated  by  Clebsch  in  1863. 

Expressing  the  coordinates  of  a  plane  cubic  by  means  of  elliptic 
functions  and  employing  their  addition  theorems,  he  deduced  with 
hardly  any  calculation  Steiner's  theorem  relating  to  the  inscribed 
polygons  and  various  theorems  concerning  conies  touching  the  curve. 
Encouraged  by  such  successes,  Clebsch  proposed  to  make  use  of 
Riemann's  theory  of  Abelian  functions  in  the  study  of  algebraic 
curves  of  any  order.  The  most  important  result  was  a  new  classifica- 
tion of  such  curves.  Instead  of  the  linear  transformation,  Clebsch 
in  harmony  with  Riemann 's  ideas  employs  the  birational  transforma- 
tion as  a  principle  of  classification.  From  this  standpoint  we  ask 
what  are  the  properties  of  algebraic  curves  which  remain  invariant 
for  such  transformation. 

Brill  and  Nother  follow  Clebsch.  Their  method  is,  however,  alge- 
braical, and  rests  on  their  celebrated  Residual  theorem  which  in 
their  hands  takes  the  place  of  Abel's  theorem.  We  mention  further 
the  investigation  of  Castelnuovo,  Weber,  Krause,  and  Segre.  An 
important  division  of  this  subject  is  the  theory  of  correspondences. 
First  studied  by  Chasles  for  curves  of  deficiency  0  in  1864,  Cayley, 
and,  immediately  after.  Brill  extended  the  theory  to  the  case  of  any 
p.    The  most  important  advance  made  in  later  years  has  been  made 


490  MATHEMATICS 

by  Hurwitz,  who  considers  the  totahty  of  possible  correspondences 
on  an  algebraic  curve,  making  use  of  the  corresponding  integrals  of 
the  first  species. 

Alongside  the  geometry  on  a  curve  is  the  vastly  more  difficult  and 
complicated  geometry  on  a  surface,  or  more  generally,  on  any  algebraic 
spread  in  n-way  space.  Starting  from  a  remark  of  Clebsch  (1868), 
Nother  made  the  first  great  step  in  his  famous  memoir  of  1868- 
74.  Further  progress  has  been  due  to  the  French  and  Italian  mathe- 
maticians. Picard,  Poincare,  and  Humbert  make  use  of  transcend- 
ental methods,  in  which  figure  prominently  double  integrals  which 
remain  finite  on  the  surface  and  single  integrals  of  total  differentials. 
On  the  other  hand,  Enriques  and  Castelnuovo  have  attacked  the 
subject  from  a  more  algebraic-geometric  standpoint  by  means  of 
linear  systems  of  algebraic  curves  on  the  surface. 

The  first  invariants  of  a  surface  were  discovered  by  Clebsch  and 
Nother;  still  others  have  been  found  by  Castelnuovo  and  Enriques 
in  connection  with  irregular  surfaces. 

Leaving  this  subject,  let  us  consider  briefly  the  geometry  of  n 
dimensions.  A  characteristic  of  nineteenth-century  mathematics 
is  the  generality  of  its  methods  and  results.  When  such  has  been 
impossible  with  the  elements  in  hand,  fresh  ones  have  been  invented; 
witness  the  introduction  of  imaginarj^  numbers  in  algebra  and  the 
function  theory,  the  ideals  of  Kummer  in  the  theory  of  numbers, 
the  line  and  plane  at  infinity  in  projective  geometry.  The  benefit 
that  analysis  derived  from  geometry  was  too  great  not  to  tempt 
mathematicians  to  free  the  latter  from  the  narrow  limits  of  three 
dimensions,  and  so  give  it  the  generality  that  the  former  has  long 
enjoyed.  The  first  pioneer  in  this  abstract  field  was  Grassmann  (1844) ; 
we  must,  however,  consider  Cayley  as  the  real  founder  of  n-dimen- 
sional  geometry  (1869).  Notable  contributions  have  been  made  by 
the  Italian  school,  Veronese,  Segre,  etc. 

Non-Euclidean  Geometry 

Each  century  takes  over  as  a  heritage  from  its  predecessor  a 
number  of  problems  whose  solution  previous  generations  of  mathe- 
maticians have  arduously  but  vainly  sought.  It  is  a  signal  achieve- 
ment of  the  nineteenth  century  to  have  triumphed  over  some  of  the 
most  celebrated  of  these  problems. 

The  most  ancient  of  them  is  the  Quadrature  of  the  Circle,  which 
already  appears  in  our  oldest  mathematical  document,  the  Papyrus 
Rhind,  B.C.  2000.  Its  impossibility  was  finally  shown  by  Lindemann 
(1882). 

Another  famous  problem  relates  to  the  solution  of  the  quintic, 
which  had  engaged  the  attention  of  mathematicians  since  the  middle 
of  the  sixteenth  century.   The  impossibility  of  expressing  its  roots  by 


MATHEMATICS   IN   THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY    491 

radicals  was  finally  shown  by  the  youthful  Abel  (1824) ,  while  Hermite 
and  Kroneker  (1858)  showed  how  they  might  be  expressed  by  the 
elliptic  modular  functions,  and  Klein  (1875)  by  means  of  the  icosa- 
hedral  irrationality. 

But  of  all  problems  which  have  come  down  from  the  past,  by  far 
the  most  celebrated  and  important  relates  to  Euclid's  parallel 
axiom.  Its  solution  has  profoundly  affected  our  views  of  space, 
and  given  rise  to  questions  even  deeper  and  more  far-reaching  which 
embrace  the  entire  foundation  of  geometry  and  our  space  conception. 
Let  us  pass  in  rapid  review  the  principal  events  of  this  great  move- 
ment. Wallis  in  the  seventeenth,  Seccheri,  Lambert,  and  Legendre 
in  the  eighteenth,  are  the  first  to  make  any  noteworthy  progress 
before  the  nineteenth  century.  The  really  profound  investigations 
of  Seccheri  and  Lambert,  strangely  enough,  were  entirely  over- 
looked by  later  writers  and  have  only  recently  come  to  light. 

In  the  nineteenth  century  non-Euclidean  geometry  develops  along 
four  directions,  which  roughly  follow  each  other  chronologically. 
Let  us  consider  them  in  order. 

The  naive-synthetic  direction.  — The  methods  employed  are  similar  to 
those  of  Euclid.  His  axioms  are  assumed  with  the  exception  of  the 
parallel  axiom;  the  resulting  geometry  is  what  is  now  called  hyper- 
bolic or  Lobatschewski's  geometry.  Its  principal  properties  are  de- 
duced, in  particular  its  trigonometry,  which  is  shown  to  be  that  of  a 
sphere  with  imaginary  radius  as  Lambert  had  divined.  As  a  specific 
result  of  these  investigations  the  long-debated  question  relating  to 
the  independence  of  the  parallel  axiom  was  finally  settled.  The  great 
names  in  this  group  are  Lobatschewski,  Bolyai,  and  Gauss.  The  first 
publications  of  Lobatschewski  are  his  Exposition  succinct  des  prin- 
cipes  de  la  geometrie  (1829) ,  and  the  Geometrische  Untersuchungen,  in 
1840.  Bolyai's  Appendix  was  published  in  1832,  As  to  the  extent 
of  Gauss's  investigations,  we  can  only  judge  from  scattered  remarks 
in  private  letters  and  his  reviews  of  books  relating  to  the  parallel 
axioms.  His  dread  of  the  Geschrei  der  Bootier,  that  is,  the  followers 
of  Kant,  prevented  him  from  publishing  his  extensive  speculations. 

The  metric-differential  direction.  — This  is  inaugurated  by  three  great 
memoirs  by  Riemann,  Helmholtz,  and  Beltrami,  all  published  in  the 
same  year,  1868. 

Beltrami,  making  use  of  results  of  Gauss  and  Minding  relating  to 
the  applicability  of  two  surfaces,  shows  that  the  hyperbolic  geometry 
of  a  plane  may  be  interpreted  on  a  surface  of  constant  negative 
curvature,  the  pseudosphere.  By  means  of  this  discovery  the  purely 
logical  and  hypothetical  system  of  Lobatschewski  and  Bolyai  takes 
on  a  form  as  concrete  and  tangible  as  the  geometry  of  a  plane. 

The  work  of  Riemann  is  as  original  as  profound.  He  considers 
space  as  an  n-dimensional  continuous  numerical  multiplicity,  which 


492  MATHEMATICS 

is  distinguished  from  the  infinity  of  other  such  multiplicities  by 
certain  well-defined  characters.  Chief  of  them  are  (1)  the  quadratic 
differential  expression  which  defines  the  length  of  an  elementary  arc, 
and  (2)  a  property  relative  to  the  displacements  of  this  multiplicity 
about  a  point.  There  are  an  infinity  of  space  multiplicities  which 
satisfy  Rieniann's  axioms.  By  extending  Gauss's  definition  of  a 
curvature  A;,  of  a  surface  at  a  point  to  curvature  of  space  at  a  point, 
by  considering  the  geodesic  surfaces  passing  through  that  point, 
Riemann  finds  that  all  these  spaces  fall  into  three  classes  according 
as  k  is  equal  to,  greater,  or  less  than  0.  For  n=3  and  A;  =  0  we  have 
Euclidean  space;  when  A;<0  we  have  the  space  found  by  Gauss, 
Lobatschewski,  and  Bolyai;  when  A;>0  we  have  the  space  first 
considered  in  the  long-forgotten  writings  of  Seccheri  and  Lambert, 
in  which  the  right  line  is  finite. 

Helmholtz,  like  Riemann,  considers  space  as  a  numerical  multiplic- 
ity. To  characterize  it  further,  Helmholtz  makes  use  of  the  notions 
of  rigid  bodies  and  free  mobility.  His  work  has  been  revised  and  ma- 
terially extended  by  Lie  from  the  standpoint  of  the  theory  of  groups. 

In  the  present  category  also  belong  important  papers  by  New- 
comb  and  Killing. 

The  projective  direction.  —  We  have  already  noticed  the  efforts  of 
the  synthetic  school  to  express  metric  properties  by  means  of  project- 
ive relations.  In  this  the  circular  points  at  infinity  were  especially 
serviceable.  An  immense  step  in  this  direction  was  taken  by  Laguerre, 
who  showed,  in  1853,  that  all  angles  might  be  expressed  as  an  anhar- 
monic  ratio  with  reference  to  these  points,  that  is,  with  reference  to 
a  certain  fixed  conic.  The  next  advance  is  made  by  Cayley  in  his 
famous  sixth  memoir  on  quantics,  in  1859.  Taking  any  fixed  conic 
(or  quadric,  for  space)  which  he  calls  the  absolute,  Cayley  introduces 
two  expressions  depending  on  the  anharmonic  ratio  with  reference 
to  the  absolute.  When  this  degenerates  into  the  circular  points 
at  infinity,  these  expressions  go  over  into  the  ordinary  expressions 
for  the  distance  between  two  points  and  the  angle  between  two 
lines.  Thus  all  metric  relations  may  be  considered  as  projective 
relations  with  respect  to  the  absolute.  Cayley  does  not  seem  to  be 
aware  of  the  relation  of  his  work  to  non-Euclidean  geometry.  This 
was  discovered  by  Klein,  in  1871.  In  fact,  according  to  the  nature  of 
the  absolute,  three  geometries  are  possible;  these  are  precisely  the 
three  already  mentioned.  Klein  has  made  many  important  contri- 
butions to  non-Euclidean  geometry.  We  mention  his  modification 
of  V.  Staudt's  definition  of  anharmonic  ratio  so  as  to  be  independ- 
ent of  the  parallel  axiom,  his  discovery  of  the  two  forms  of  Rie- 
mann's  space,  and  finally  his  contributions  to  a  class  of  geometries 
first  noticed  by  Clifford  and  which  are  characterized  by  the  fact  that 
only  certain  of  its  motions  affect  space  as  a  whole. 


MATHEMATICS   IN   THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY    493 

As  a  result  of  all  these  investigations,  both  in  the  projective  as 
also  in  the  metric  differential  direction,  we  are  led  irresistibly  to  the 
same  conclusion,  namely:  The  facts  of  experience  can  be  explained 
by  all  three  geometries  when  the  constant  k  is  taken  small  enough. 
It  is,  therefore,  merely  a  question  of  convenience  whether  we  adopt 
the  parabolic,  hyperbolic,  or  elliptic  geometry. 

The  critical  synthetic  direction  represents  a  return  to  the  old  sya.- 
thetic  methods  of  Euclid,  Lobatschewski,  and  Bolyai,  with  the  added 
feature  of  a  refined  and  exacting  logic.  Its  principal  object  is  no 
longer  a  study  of  non-Euclidean  but  of  Euclidean  geometry.  Its 
aim  is  to  establish  a  system  of  axioms  for  our  ordinary  space  which 
is  complete,  compatible,  and  irreducible.  The  fundamental  terms 
point,  line,  plane,  between,  congruent,  etc.,  are  introduced  as  ab- 
stract marks  whose  properties  are  determined  by  inter-relations  in 
the  form  of  axioms.  Geometric  intuition  has  no  place  in  this  order 
of  ideas  which  regards  geometry  as  a  mere  division  of  pure  logic. 
The  efforts  of  this  school  have  already  been  crowned  with  eminent 
success,  and  much  may  be  expected  from  it  in  the  future.  Its  leaders 
are  Peano,  Veronese,  Fieri,  Padoa,  Burali-Forti,  and  Levi-Civitta,  in 
Italy,  Pasch  and  Hilbert  in  Germany,  and  Moore  in  America. 

Closing  at  this  point  our  hasty  and  imperfect  survey  of  mathe- 
matics in  the  last  century,  let  us  endeavor  to  sum  up  its  main  charac- 
teristics. What  strikes  us  at  once  is  its  colossal  proportions  and  rapid 
growth  in  nearly  all  directions,  the  great  variety  of  its  branches,  the 
generality  and  complexity  of  its  methods;  an  inexhaustible  creative 
imagination,  the  fearless  introduction  and  employment  of  ideal 
elements,  and  an  appreciation  for  a  refined  and  logical  development 
of  all  its  parts. 

We  who  stand  on  the  threshold  of  a  new  century  can  look  back  on 
an  era  of  unparalleled  progress.  Looking  into  the  future,  an  equally 
bright  prospect  greets  our  eyes;  on  all  sides  fruitful  fields  of  re- 
search invite  our  labor  and  promise  easy  and  rich  returns. 

Surely  this  is  the  golden  age  of  mathematics. 


SECTION  A— ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS 


SECTION  A  — ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS 

{HaU  9,  September  22,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:  Professor  E.  H.  Moore,  University  of  Chicago. 
Speakers:   Professor  Charles  Emile  Picakd,  The  Sorbonne;  Member  of  the 
Institute  of  France. 
Professor  Heinrich  Maschke,  University  of  Chicago. 
Secretary:  Professor  A.  G.  Bliss,  University  of  Chicago. 


ON  THE  DEVELOPMENT  OF  MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS 
AND  ITS  RELATIONS  TO  SOME  OTHER  SCIENCES 

BY    CHARLES    EMILE    PICARD 

{Translated  from  the  French  by  Professor  George  Bruce  Halsted,  Kenyan  College) 

[Charles  Emile  Picard,  Professor  of  Higher  Algebra  and  Higher  Analysis,  Uni- 
versity of  Paris;  also  Professor  of  General  Mechanics,  TEcole  Centrale  des 
Arts  et  Manufactures,  Paris,  b.  Paris,  France,  July  24,  1856.  LL.D.  Clark 
University,  Glasgow  University,  University  of  Christiania.  Member  of  In- 
stitute of  France;  Academy  of  Science,  Berlin,  St.  Petersburg,  Bologna, 
Boston,  Turin,  Copenhagen,  Washington,  and  many  others;  Mathematical 
Society  of  London.  Former  President  of  Mathematical  Society  of  France, 
Mathematical  Societies  of  London  and  Kharkow,  and  many  other  math- 
ematical societies.  Author  and  editor  of  Memoirs,  Traits  and  Discussions 
of  Mathematics;    Theory  of  Algebraic  Functions  of  Two  Variables.] 

It  is  one  of  the  objects  of  a  congress  such  as  this  which  now 
brings  us  together,  to  show  the  bonds  between  the  diverse  parts  of 
science  taken  in  its  most  extended  acceptation.  So  the  organizers 
of  this  meeting  have  insisted  that  the  relations  between  different 
sections  should  be  put  in  evidence. 

To  undertake  a  study  of  this  sort,  somewhat  indeterminate  in 
character,  it  is  necessary  to  forget  that  all  is  in  all;  in  what  con- 
cerns algebra  and  analysis,  a  Pythagorean  would  be  dismayed  at  the 
extent  of  his  task,  remembering  the  celebrated  formula  of  the  school: 
"  Things  are  numbers."  From  this  point  of  view  my  subject  would 
be  inexhaustible. 

But  I,  for  the  best  of  reasons,  will  make  no  such  pretensions. 

In  casting  merely  a  glance  over  the  development  of  our  science 
through  the  ages,  and  particularly  in  the  last  century,  I  hope  to  be 
able  to  characterize  sufficiently  the  role  of  mathematical  analysis  in 
its  relations  to  certain  other  sciences. 

I 

It  would  appear  natural  to  commence  by  speaking  of  the  concept 
itself  of  whole  number;  but  this  subject  is  not  alone  of  logical  order, 


498         ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS 

it  is  also  of  order  historic  and  psychologic,  and  would  draw  us  away 
into  too  many  discussions. 

Since  the  concept  of  number  has  been  sifted,  in  it  have  been  found 
unfathomable  depths;  thus,  it  is  a  question  still  pending  to  know, 
between  the  two  forms,  the  cardinal  number  and  the  ordinal  number, 
under  which  the  idea  of  number  presents  itself,  which  of  the  two  is 
anterior  to  the  other,  that  is  to  say,  whether  the  idea  of  number 
properly  so  called  is  anterior  to  that  of  order,  or  if  it  is  the  inverse. 

It  seems  that  the  geometer-logician  neglects  too  much  in  these 
questions  psychology  and  the  lessons  uncivilized  races  give  us;  it 
would  seem  to  result  from  these  studies  that  the  priority  is  with  the 
cardinal  number. 

It  may  also  be  there  is  no  general  response  to  the  question,  the 
response  varying  according  to  races  and  according  to  mentalities. 

I  have  sometimes  thought,  on  this  subject,  of  the  distinction  be- 
tween auditives  and  visuals,  auditives  favoring  the  ordinal  theory, 
visuals  the  cardinal. 

But  I  will  not  linger  on  this  ground  full  of  snares;  I  fear  that  our 
modern  school  of  logicians  with  difficulty  comes  to  agreement  with 
the  ethnologists  and  biologists;  these  latter  in  questions  of  origin 
are  always  dominated  by  the  evolution  idea,  and,  for  more  than  one 
of  them,  logic  is  only  the  resume  of  ancestral  experience.  Mathe- 
maticians are  even  reproached  with  postulating  in  principle  that 
there  is  a  human  mind  in  some  way  exterior  to  things,  and  that  it 
has  its  logic.  We  must,  however,  submit  to  this,  on  pain  of  con- 
structing nothing.  We  need  this  point  of  departure,  and  certainly, 
supposing  it  to  have  evolved  during  the  course  of  prehistoric  time, 
this  logic  of  the  human  mind  was  perfectly  fixed  at  the  time  of  the 
oldest  geometric  schools,  those  of  Greece;  their  works  appear  to 
have  been  its  first  code,  as  is  expressed  by  the  story  of  Plato  writing 
over  the  door  of  his  school,  "Let  no  one  not  a  geometer  enter 
here." 

Long  before  the  bizarre  word  algebra  was  derived  from  the  Arabic, 
expressing,  it  would  seem,  the  operation  by  which  equalities  are 
reduced  to  a  certain  canonic  form,  the  Greeks  had  made  algebra 
without  knowing  it;  relations  more  intimate  could  not  be  imagined 
than  those  binding  together  their  algebra  and  their  geometry,  or 
rather,  one  would  be  embarrassed  to  classify,  if  there  were  occasion, 
their  geometric  algebra,  in  which  they  reason  not  on  numbers  but  on 
magnitudes. 

Among  the  Greeks  also  we  find  a  geometric  arithmetic,  and  one  of 
the  most  interesting  phases  of  its  development  is  the  conflict  which, 
among  the  Pythagoreans,  arose  in  this  subject  between  number  and 
magnitude,  apropos  of  irrationals. 

Though  the  Greeks  cultivated  the  abstract  study  of  numbers,  called 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  MATHEMATICAL   ANALYSIS     499 

by  them  arithmetic,  their  speculative  spirit  showed  httle  taste  for 
practical  calculation,  which  they  called  logistic. 

In  remote  antiquity,  the  Egyptians  and  the  Chaldeans,  and  later 
the  Hindus  and  the  Arabs,  carried  far  the  science  of  calculation. 

They  were  led  on  by  practical  needs;  logistic  preceded  arithmetic, 
as  land-surveying  and  geodesy  opened  the  way  to  geometry;  in  the 
same  way  trigonometry  developed  under  the  influence  of  the  in- 
creasing needs  of  astronomy. 

The  history  of  science  at  its  beginnings  shows  a  close  relation 
between  pure  and  applied  mathematics;  this  we  shall  meet  again 
constantly  in  the  course  of  this  study. 

We  have  remained  up  to  this  point  in  the  domain  which  ordinary 
language  calls  elementary  algebra  and  arithmetic. 

In  fact,  from  the  time  that  the  incommensurability  of  certain 
magnitudes  had  been  recognized,  the  infinite  had  made  its  appearance, 
and,  from  the  time  of  the  sophisms  of  Zeno  on  the  impossibility  of 
motion,  the  summation  of  geometric  progressions  must  have  been 
considered. 

The  procedures  of  exhaustion  which  are  found  in  Eudoxus  and  in 
Euclid  appertain  already  to  the  integral  calculus,  and  Archimedes 
calculates  definite  integrals. 

Mechanics  also  appeared  in  his  treatise  on  the  quadrature  of  the 
parabola,  since  he  first  finds  the  surface  of  the  segment  bounded  by 
an  arc  of  a  parabola  and  its  chord  w4th  the  help  of  the  theorem  of 
moments;  this  is  the  first  example  of  the  relations  between  me- 
chanics and  analysis,  which  since  have  not  ceased  developing.. 

The  infinitesimal  method  of  the  Greek  geometers  for  the  measure 
of  volumes  raised  questions  whose  interest  is  even  to-day  not  ex- 
hausted. 

In  plane  geometry,  tw^o  polygons  of  the  same  area  are  either 
equivalent  or  equivalent-by-completion,  that  is  to  say,  can  be  de- 
composed into  a  finite  number  of  triangles  congruent  in  pairs,  or 
may  be  regarded  as  differences  of  polygons  susceptible  of  such  a 
partition. 

It  is  not  the  same  for  the  geometry  of  space,  and  we  have  lately 
learned  that  stereometry  cannot,  like  planimetry,  get  on  without 
recourse  to  procedures  of  exhaustion  or  of  limit,  which  require  the 
axiom  of  continuity  or  the  Archimedes  assumption. 

Without  insisting  further,  this  hasty  glance  at  antiquity  shows 
how  completely  then  were  amalgamated  algebra,  arithmetic,  geo- 
metry, and  the  first  endeavors  at  integral  calculus  and  mechanics,  to 
the  point  of  its  being  impossible  to  recall  separately  their  history. 

In  the  Middle  Ages  and  the  Renaissance,  the  geometric  algebra  of 
the  ancients  separated  from  geometry.  Little  by  little  algebra 
properly  so  called  arrived  at  independence,  with  its  symbolism  and 


500  ALGEBRA   AND  ANALYSIS 

its  notation  more  and  more  perfected;  thus  was  created  this  lan- 
guage so  admirably  clear,  which  brings  about  for  thought  a  veritable 
economy  and  renders  further  progress  possible. 

This  is  also  the  moment  when  distinct  divisions  are  organized. 

Trigonometry,  which,  in  antiquity,  had  been  only  an  auxiliary  of 
astronomy,  is  developed  independently;  toward  the  same  time  the 
logarithm  appears,  and  essential  elements  are  thus  put  in  evidence. 

II 

In  the  seventeenth  century,  the  analytic  geometry  of  Descartes, 
distinct  from  what  I  have  just  called  the  geometric  algebra  of  the 
Greeks  by  the  general  and  systematic  ideas  which  are  at  its  base, 
and  the  new-born  dynamic  were  the  origin  of  the  greatest  progress  of 
analysis. 

When  Galileo,  starting  from  the  hypothesis  that  the  velocity  of 
heavy  bodies  in  their  fall  is  proportional  to  the  time,  from  this 
deduced  the  law  of  the  distances  passed  over,  to  verify  it  afterward 
by  experiment,  he  took  up  again  the  road  upon  which  Archimedes 
had  formerly  entered  and  on  which  would  follow  after  him  Cavalieri, 
Fermat,  and  others  still,  even  to  Newton  and  Leibnitz.  The  integral 
calculus  of  the  Greek  geometers  was  born  again  in  the  kinematic  of 
the  great  Florentine  physicist. 

As  to  the  calculus  of  derivatives  or  of  differentials,  it  was  founded 
with  precision  apropos  of  the  drawing  of  tangents. 

In  reality,  the  origin  of  the  notion  of  derivative  is  in  the  confused 
sense  of  the  mobility  of  things  and  of  the  rapidity  more  or  less  great 
with  which  phenomena  happen;  this  is  well  expressed  by  the  words 
fluents  and  fluxions,  which  Newton  used,  and  which  one  might 
suppose  borrowed  from  old  Heraclitus. 

The  points  of  view  taken  by  the  founders  of  the  science  of  motion, 
Galileo,  Huygens,  and  Newton,  had  an  enormous  influence  on  the 
orientation  of  mathematical  analysis. 

It  was  with  Galileo  an  intuition  of  genius  to  discover  that,  in 
natural  phenomena,  the  determining  circumstances  of  the  motion 
produce  accelerations:  this  must  have  conducted  to  the  statement 
of  the  principle  that  the  rapidity  with  which  the  dynamic  state  of 
a  system  changes  depends  in  a  determinate  manner  on  its  static  state 
alone.  In  a  more  general  way  we  reach  the  postulate  that  the  in- 
finitesimal changes,  of  whatever  nature  they  may  be,  occurring  in 
a  system  of  bodies,  depend  uniquely  on  the  actual  state  of  this 
system. 

In  what  degree  are  the  exceptions  apparent  or  real?  This  is  a  ques- 
tion which  was  raised  only  later  and  which  I  put  aside  for  the 
moment. 

From  the  principles  enunciated  becomes  clear  a  point  of  capital 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS     501 

importance  for  the  analyst:  Phenomena  are  ruled  by  differential 
equations  which  can  be  formed  when  observation  and  experiment 
have  made  known  for  each  category  of  phenomena  certain  physical 
laws. 

We  understand  the  unlimited  hopes  conceived  from  these  results. 
As  Bertrand  says  in  the  preface  of  his  treatise,  "The  early  successes 
were  at  first  such  that  one  might  suppose  all  the  difficulties  of  science 
surmounted  in  advance,  and  believe  that  the  geometers,  without 
being  longer  distracted  by  the  elaboration  of  pure  mathematics, 
could  turn  their  meditations  exclusively  toward  the  study  of  the 
natural  laws." 

This  was  to  admit  gratuitously  that  the  problems  of  analysis,  to 
which  one  was  led,  would  not  present  very  grave  difficulties. 

Despite  the  disillusions  the  future  was  to  bring,  this  capital  point 
remained,  that  the  problems  had  taken  a  precise  form,  and  that  a 
classification  could  be  established  in  the  difficulties  to  be  surmounted. 

There  was,  therefore,  an  immense  advance,  one  of  the  greatest 
ever  made  by  the  human  mind.  We  understand  also  why  the  theory 
of  differential  equations  acquired  a  considerable  importance. 

I  have  anticipated  somewhat,  in  presenting  things  under  a  form 
so  analytic.  Geometry  was  intermingled  in  all  this  progress.  Huy- 
gens,  for  example,  followed  always  by  preference  the  ancients,  and 
his  Horologium  oscillatorium  rests  at  the  same  time  on  infinitesi- 
mal geometry  and  mechanics;  in  the  same  way,  in  the  Principia 
of  Newton,  the  methods  followed  are  synthetic. 

It  is,  above  all,  with  Leibnitz  that  science  takes  the  paths  which 
were  to  lead  to  what  we  call  mathematical  analysis;  it  is  he  who, 
for  the  first  time,  in  the  latter  years  of  the  seventeenth  century, 
pronounces  the  word  function. 

By  his  systematic  spirit,  by  the  numerous  problems  he  treated, 
even  as  his  disciples  James  and  John  Bernoulli,  he  established  in  a 
final  way  the  power  of  the  doctrines  to  the  edification  of  which  had 
successively  contributed  a  long  series  of  thinkers  from  the  distant 
times  of  Eudoxus  and  of  Archimedes. 

The  eighteenth  century  showed  the  extreme  fecundity  of  the  new 
methods.  That  was  a  strange  time,  the  era  of  mathematical  duels 
w^here  geometers  hurled  defiance,  combats  not  always  without 
acrimony,  when  Leibnitzians  and  Newtonians  encountered  in  the 
lists. 

From  the  purely  analytic  point  of  view,  the  classification  and  study 
of  simple  functions  is  particularly  interesting;  the  function  idea,  on 
which  analysis  rests,  is  thus  developed  little  by  little. 

The  celebrated  works  of  Euler  hold  then  a  considerable  place. 
However,  the  numerous  problems  which  present  themselves  to  the 
mathematicians  leave  no   time  for  a  scrutiny  of  principles;    the 


502  ALGEBRA  AND   ANALYSIS 

foundations  themselves  of  the  doctrine  are  elucidated  slowly,  and 
the  mot  attributed  to  d'Alembert,  "AUez  en  avant  et  la  foi  vous 
viendra, "  is  very  characteristic  of  this  epoch. 

Of  all  the  problems  started  at  the  end  of  the  seventeenth  century 
or  during  the  first  half  of  the  eighteenth,  it  will  suffice  for  me  to  recall 
those  isoperimetric  problems  which  gave  birth  to  the  calculus  of 
variations. 

I  prefer  to  insist  on  the  interpenetration  still  more  intimate 
between  analysis  and  mechanics  when,  after  the  inductive  period  of 
the  first  age  of  dynamics,  the  deductive  period  was  reached  where  one 
strove  to  give  a  final  form  to  the  principles.  The  mathematical  and 
formal  development  played  then  the  essential  role,  and  the  analytic 
language  was  indispensable  to  the  greatest  extension  of  these  prin- 
ciples. 

There  are  moments  in  the  history  of  the  sciences  and,  perhaps,  of 
society,  when  the  spirit  is  sustained  and  carried  forward  by  the  words 
and  the  symbols  it  has  created,  and  when  generalizations  present 
themselves  with  the  least  effort.  Such  was  particularly  the  role  of 
analysis  in  the  formal  development  of  mechanics. 

Allow  me  a  remark  just  here.  It  is  often  said  an  equation  contains 
only  what  one  has  put  into  it.  It  is  easy  to  answer,  first,  that  the 
new  form  under  which  one  finds  the  things  constitutes  often  of  itself 
an  important  discovery. 

But  sometimes  there  is  more;  analysis,  by  the  simple  play  of 
its  symbols,  may  suggest  generalizations  far  surpassing  the  primitive 
outline.  Is  it  not  so  with  the  principle  of  virtual  velocities,  of  which 
the  first  idea  comes  from  the  simplest  mechanisms;  the  analytic 
form  which  translates  it  will  suggest  extensions  leading  far  from  the 
point  of  departure. 

In  the  same  sense,  it  is  not  just  to  say  analysis  has  created  nothing, 
since  these  more  general  conceptions  are  its  work.  Still  another 
example  is  furnished  us  by  Lagrange's  system  of  equations;  here 
calculus  transformations  have  given  the  type  of  differential  equations 
to  which  one  tends  to  carry  back  to-day  the  notion  of  mechanical 
explanation. 

There  are  in  science  few  examples  comparable  to  this,  of  the 
importance  of  the  form  of  an  analytic  relation  and  of  the  power  of 
generalization  of  which  it  may  be  capable. 

It  is  very  clear  that,  in  each  case,  the  generalizations  suggested 
should  be  made  precise  by  an  appeal  to  observation  and  experiment, 
then  it  is  still  the  calculus  which  searches  out  distant  consequences 
for  checks,  but  this  is  an  order  of  ideas  which  I  need  not  broach  here. 
Under  the  impulse  of  the  problems  set  by  geometry,  mechanics, 
and  physics,  we  see  develop  or  take  birth  almost  all  the  great  divisions 
of  analysis.    First  were  met  equations  with  a  single  independent  vari- 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS    503 

able.  Soon  appear  partml  differential  equations,  with  vibrating  cords, 
the  mechanics  of  fluids  and  the  infinitesimal  geometry  of  surfaces. 

This  was  a  wholly  new  analytic  w^orld;  the  origin  itself  of  the 
problems  treated  was  an  aid  which  from  the  first  steps  permits  no 
wandering,  and  in  the  hands  of  Monge  geometry  rendered  useful 
services  to  the  new-born  theories. 

But  of  all  the  applications  of  analysis,  none  had  then  more  renown 
than  the  problems  of  celestial  mechanics  set  by  the  knowledge  of  the 
law  of  gravitation  and  to  which  the  greatest  geometers  gave  their 
names. 

Theory  never  had  a  more  beautiful  triumph;  perhaps  one  might 
add  that  it  was  too  complete,  because  it  was  at  this  moment  above 
all  that  were  conceived  for  natural  philosophy  the  hopes  at  least 
premature  of  which  I  spoke  above. 

In  all  this  period,  especially  in  the  second  half  of  the  eighteenth 
century,  what  strikes  us  with  admiration  and  is  also  somewhat 
confusing,  is  the  extreme  importance  of  the  applications  realized, 
while  the  pure  theory  appeared  still  so  iU  assured.  One  perceives  it 
when  certain  questions  are  raised  like  the  degree  of  arbitrariness  in 
the  integral  of  vibrating  cords,  which  gives  place  to  an  interminable 
and  inconclusive  discussion. 

Lagrange  appreciated  these  insufficiencies  when  he  published  his 
theory  of  analytic  functions,  where  he  strove  to  give  a  precise  foun- 
dation to  analysis. 

One  cannot  too  much  admire  the  marvelous  presentiment  he  had 
of  the  role  which  the  functions,  which  with  him  we  call  analytic, 
were  to  play;  but  we  may  confess  that  we  stand  astonished  before 
the  demonstration  he  believed  to  have  given  of  the  possibility  of  the 
development  of  a  function  in  Taylor's  series. 

The  exigencies  in  questions  of  pure  analysis  were  less  at  this 
epoch.  Confiding  in  intuition,  one  was  content  with  certain  probabil- 
ities, and  agreed  implicitly  about  certain  hypotheses  that  it  seemed 
useless  to  formulate  in  an  explicit  way;  in  reality,  one  had  con- 
fidence in  the  ideas  which  so  many  times  had  shown  themselves 
fecund,  which  is  very  nearly  the  mot  of  d'Alembert. 

The  demand  for  rigor  in  mathematics  has  had  its  successive 
approximations,  and  in  this  regard  our  sciences  have  not  the  absolute 
character  so  many  people  attribute  to  them. 

Ill 

We  have  now  reached  the  first  years  of  the  nineteenth  century. 
As  we  have  explained,  the  great  majority  of  the  analytic  researches 
had,  in  the  eighteenth  century,  for  occasion  a  problem  of  geometry, 
and  especially  of  mechanics  and  of  physics,  and  we  have  scarcely 
found  the  logical  and  aesthetic  preoccupations  which  are  to  give  a 


504  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS 

physiognomy  so  different  to  so  many  mathematical  works,  above  all 
in  the  latter  two  thirds  of  the  nineteenth  century. 

Not  to  anticipate,  however,  after  so  many  examples  of  the  in- 
fluences of  physics  on  the  developments  of  analysis,  we  meet  still  a 
new  one,  and  one  of  the  most  memorable,  in  Fourier's  theory  of  heat. 
He  commences  by  forming  the  partial  differential  equations  which 
govern  temperature. 

What  are  for  a  partial  differential  equation  the  conditions  at  the 
limits  permitting  the  determination  of  a  solution? 

For  Fourier,  the  conditions  are  suggested  by  the  physical  problem, 
and  the  methods  that  he  followed  have  served  as  models  to  the 
physicist-geometers  of  the  first  half  of  the  last  century. 

One  of  these  consists  in  forming  a  series  with  certain  simple  solu- 
tions. Fourier  thus  obtained  the  first  types  of  developments  more 
general  than  the  trigonometric  developments,  as  in  the  problem  of 
the  cooling  of  a  sphere,  where  he  applies  his  theory  to  the  terrestrial 
globe,  and  investigates  the  law  which  governs  the  variations  of 
temperature  in  the  ground,  trying  to  go  even  as  far  as  numerical 
applications. 

In  the  face  of  so  many  beautiful  results,  we  understand  the  enthu- 
siasm of  Fourier  which  scintillates  from  every  line  of  his  preliminary 
discourse.  Speaking  of  mathematical  analysis,  he  says,  "There  could 
not  be  a  language  more  universal,  more  simple,  more  exempt  from 
errors  and  from  obscurities,  that  is  to  say,  more  worthy  to  express 
the  invariable  relations  of  natural  things.  Considered  under  this 
point  of  view,  it  is  as  extended  as  nature  herself;  it  defines  all  sen- 
sible relations,  measures  times,  spaces,  forces,  temperatures.  This 
difficult  science  forms  slowly,  but  it  retains  all  the  principles  once 
acquired.  It  grows  and  strengthens  without  cease  in  the  midst  of 
so  many  errors  of  the  human  mind." 

The  eulogy  is  magnificent,  but  permeating  it  we  see  the  tendency 
which  makes  all  analysis  uniquely  an  auxiliary,  however  incom- 
parable, of  the  natural  sciences,  a  tendency,  in  conformity,  as  we 
have  seen,  with  the  development  of  science  during  the  preceding  two 
centuries;  but  we  reach  just  here  an  epoch  where  new  tendencies 
appear. 

Poisson  having  in  a  report  on  the  Fundamenta  recalled  the  re- 
proach made  by  Fourier  to  Abel  and  Jacobi  of  not  having  occupied 
themselves  preferably  with  the  movement  of  heat,  Jacobi  wrote  to 
Legendre:  "It  is  true  that  Monsieur  Fourier  held  the  view  that 
the  principal  aim  of  mathematics  was  public  utility,  and  the  ex- 
planation of  natural  phenomena;  but  a  philosopher  such  as  he 
should  have  known  that  the  unique  aim  of  science  is  the  honor  of 
the  human  spirit,  and  that  from  this  point  of  view  a  question  about 
numbers  is  as  important  as  a  question  about  the  system  of  the 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS     505 

world."  This  was  without  doubt  also  the  opinion  of  the  grand  geo- 
meter of  Goettingen,  who  called  mathematics  the  queen  of  the  sciences, 
and  arithmetic  the  queen  of  mathematics. 

It  would  be  ridiculous  to  oppose  one  to  the  other  these  two 
tendencies;  the  harmony  of  our  science  is  in  their  synthesis. 

The  time  was  about  to  arrive  when  one  would  feel  the  need  of 
inspecting  the  foundations  of  the  edifice,  and  of  making  the  inventory 
of  accumulated  wealth,  using  more  of  the  critical  spirit.  Mathematical 
thought  was  about  to  gather  more  force  by  retiring  into  itself;  the 
problems  were  exhausted  for  a  time,  and  it  is  not  well  for  all  seekers 
to  stay  on  the  same  road.  Moreover,  difficulties  and  paradoxes 
remaining  unexplained  made  necessary  the  progress  of  pure  theory. 

The  path  on  which  this  should  move  was  traced  in  its  large  outlines, 
and  there  it  could  move  with  independence  without  necessarily  losing 
contact  with  the  problems  set  by  geometry,  mechanics,  and  physics. 

At  the  same  time  more  interest  was  to  attach  to  the  philosophic 
and  artistic  side  of  mathematics,  confiding  in  a  sort  of  preestab- 
lished  harmony  between  our  logical  and  aesthetic  satisfactions  and  the 
necessities  of  future  applications. 

Let  us  recall  rapidly  certain  points  in  the  history  of  the  revision 
of  principles  where  Gauss,  Cauchy,  and  Abel  likewise  were  laborers 
of  the  first  hour.  Precise  definitions  of  continuous  functions,  and  their 
most  immediate  properties,  simple  rules  on  the  convergence  of  series, 
were  formulated;  and  soon  was  established,  under  very  general 
conditions,  the  possibility  of  trigonometric  developments,  legiti- 
matizing thus  the  boldness  of  Fourier. 

Certain  geometric  intuitions  relative  to  areas  and  to  arcs  give 
place  to  rigorous  demonstration.  The  geometers  of  the  eighteenth 
century  had  necessarily  sought  to  give  account  of  the  degree  of  the 
generality  of  the  solution  of  ordinary  differential  equations.  Their 
likeness  to  equations  of  finite  differences  led  easily  to  the  result;  but 
the  demonstration  so  conducted  must  not  be  pressed  very  close. 

Lagrange,  in  his  lessons  on  the  calculus  of  functions,  had  intro- 
duced greater  precision,  and  starting  from  Taylor's  series,  he  saw 
that  the  equation  of  order  m  leaves  indeterminate  the  function, 
and  its  w  —  1  first  derivatives  for  the  initial  value  of  the  variable; 
we  are  not  surprised  that  Lagrange  did  not  set  himself  the  question 
of  convergence. 

In  twenty  or  thirty  years  the  exigencies  in  the  rigor  of  proofs  had 
grown.  One  knew  that  the  two  preceding  modes  of  demonstration 
are  susceptible  of  all  the  precision  necessary. 

For  the  first,  there  was  need  of  no  new  principle;  for  the  second 
it  was  necessary  that  the  theory  should  develop  in  a  new  way.  Up 
to  this  point,  the  functions  and  the  variables  had  remained  real. 
The  consideration  of  complex  variables  comes  to  extend  the  field  of 


506  ALGEBRA   AND   ANALYSIS 

analysis.  The  functions  of  a  complex  variable  with  unique  derivative 
are  necessarily  developable  in  Taylor's  series;  we  come  back  thus 
to  the  mode  of  development  of  which  the  author  of  the  theory  of 
analytic  functions  had  understood  the  interest,  but  of  which  the 
importance  could  not  be  put  fully  in  evidence  in  limiting  one's  self 
to  real  variables.  They  also  owe  the  grand  role  that  they  have  not 
ceased  to  play  to  the  facility  with  which  we  can  manage  them,  and 
to  their  convenience  in  calculation. 

The  general  theorems  of  the  theory  of  analytic  functions  permitted 
to  reply  with  precision  to  questions  remaining  up  to  that  time  un- 
decided, such  as  the  degree  of  generality  of  the  integrals  of  differential 
equations.  It  became  possible  to  push  even  to  the  end  the  demon- 
stration sketched  by  Lagrange  for  an  ordinary  differential  equa- 
tion. For  a  partial  differential  equation  or  a  system  of  such  equations, 
precise  theorems  were  established.  It  is  not  that  on  this  latter  point 
the  results  obtained,  however  important  they  may  be,  resolve 
completely  the  diverse  questions  that  may  be  set;  because  in  mathe- 
matical physics,  and  often  in  geometry,  the  conditions  at  the  limits 
are  susceptible  of  forms  so  varied  that  the  problem  called  Cauchy's 
appears  often  under  very  severe  form.  I  will  shortly  return  to  this 
capital  point. 

IV 

Without  restricting  ourselves  to  the  historic  order,  we  will  follow 
the  development  of  mathematical  physics  during  the  last  century, 
in  so  far  as  it  interests  analysis. 

The  problems  of  calorific  equilibrium  lead  to  the  equation  already 
encountered  by  Laplace  in  the  study  of  attraction.  Few  equations 
have  been  the  object  of  so  many  works  as  this  celebrated  equation. 
The  conditions  at  the  limits  may  be  of  divers  forms.  The  simplest 
case  is  that  of  the  calorific  equilibrium  of  a  body  of  which  we  main- 
tain the  elements  of  the  surface  at  given  temperatures;  from  the 
physical  point  of  view,  it  may  be  regarded  as  evident  that  the  tem- 
perature, continuous  within  the  interior  since  no  source  of  heat  is 
there,  is  determined  when  it  is  given  at  the  surface. 

A  more  general  case  is  that  where,  the  state  remaining  permanent, 
there  might  be  radiation  toward  the  outside  with  an  emissive  power 
varying  on  the  surface  in  accordance  with  a  given  law;  in  particular 
the  temperature  may  be  given  on  one  portion,  while  there  is  radiation 
on  another  portion. 

These  questions,  which  are  not  yet  resolved  in  their  greatest  gen- 
erality, have  greatly  contributed  to  the  orientation  of  the  theory  of 
partial  differential  equations.  They  have  called  attention  to  types  of 
determinations  of  integrals,  which  would  not  have  presented  them- 
selves in  remaining  at  a  point  of  view  purely  abstract. 


DEVELOPMENT   OF   MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS     507 

Laplace's  equation  had  been  met  already  in  hydrodynamics  and 
in  the  study  of  attraction  inversely  as  the  square  of  the  distance. 
This  latter  theory  has  led  to  putting  in  evidence  the  most  essential 
elements,  such  as  the  potentials  of  simple  strata  and  of  double 
strata.  Analytic  combinations  of  the  highest  importance  were  there 
met,  which  since  have  been  notably  generalized,  such  as  Green's 
formula. 

The  fundamental  problems  of  static  electricity  belong  to  the 
same  order  of  ideas,  and  that  was  surely  a  beautiful  triumph  for 
theory,  the  discovery  of  the  celebrated  theorem  on  electric  phe- 
nomena in  the  interior  of  hollow  conductors,  which  later  Faraday 
rediscovered  experimentally,  without  having  known  of  Green's 
memoir. 

All  this  magnificent  ensemble  has  remained  the  type  of  the  theories 
already  old  of  mathematical  physics,  which  seem  to  us  almost  to 
have  attained  perfection,  and  which  exercise  stiU  so  happy  an  in- 
fluence on  the  progress  of  pure  analysis  in  suggesting  to  it  the  most 
beautiful  problems.  The  theory  of  functions  offers  us  another  mem- 
orable affiliation. 

There  the  analytic  transformations  which  come  into  play  are  not 
distinct  from  those  we  have  met  in  the  permanent  movement  of 
heat.  Certain  fundamental  problems  of  the  theory  of  functions  of 
a  complex  variable  lost  then  their  abstract  enunciation  to  take  a 
physical  form,  such  as  that  of  the  distribution  of  temperature  on 
a  closed  surface  of  any  connection  and  not  radiating,  in  calorific 
equilibrium  with  two  sources  of  heat  which  necessarily  correspond 
to  flows  equal  and  of  contrary  signs.  Transposing,  we  face  a  ques- 
tion relative  to  Abelian  integrals  of  the  third  species  in  the  theory  of 
algebraic  curves. 

The  examples  which  precede,  where  we  have  envisaged  only  the 
equations  of  heat  and  of  attraction,  show  that  the  influence  of 
physical  theories  has  been  exercised  not  only  on  the  general  nature 
of  the  problems  to  be  solved,  but  even  in  the  details  of  the  analytic 
transformations.  Thus  is  currently  designated  in  recent  memoirs  on 
partial  differential  equations  under  the  name  of  Green's  formula, 
a  formula  inspired  by  the  primitive  formula  of  the  English  physicist. 
The  theory  of  dynamic  electricity  and  that  of  magnetism,  with 
Ampere  and  Gauss,  have  been  the  origin  of  important  progress;  the 
study  of  curvilinear  integrals  and  that  of  the  integrals  of  surfaces 
have  taken  thence  all  their  developments,  and  formulas,  such  as 
that  of  Stokes  which  might  also  be  called  Ampere's  formula,  have 
appeared  for  the  first  time  in  memoirs  on  physics.  The  equations 
of  the  propagation  of  electricity,  to  which  are  attached  the  names  of 
Ohm  and  Kirchoff,  while  presenting  a  great  analogy  with  those  of 
heat,  offer  often  conditions  at  the  Hmits  a  little  different;  we  know 


508  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS 

all  that  telegraphy  by  cables  owes  to  the  profound  discussion  of  a 
Fourier's  equation  carried  over  into  electricity. 

The  equations  long  ago  written  of  hydrodynamics,  the  equations 
of  the  theory  of  electricity,  those  of  Maxwell  and  of  Hertz  in  electro- 
magnetism,  have  offered  problems  analogous  to  those  recalled  above, 
but  under  conditions  still  more  varied.  Many  unsurmounted  diffi- 
culties are  there  met  with;  but  how  many  beautiful  results  we  owe 
to  the  study  of  particular  cases,  whose  number  one  would  wish  to 
see  increase.  To  be  noted  also  as  interesting  at  once  to  analysis  and 
physics  are  the  profound  differences  which  the  propagation  may 
present  according  to  the  phenomena  studied.  With  equations  such 
as  those  of  sound,  we  have  propagation  by  waves;  with  the  equa- 
tion of  heat,  each  variation  is  felt  instantly  at  every  distance,  but 
very  little  at  a  very  great  distance,  and  we  cannot  then  speak  of 
velocity  of  propagation. 

In  other  cases  of  which  Kirchoff's  equation  relative  to  the  propa- 
gation of  electricity  with  induction  and  capacity  offers  the  simplest 
type,  there  is  a  wave  front  with  a  velocity  determined  but  with  a 
remainder  behind  which  does  not  vanish. 

These  diverse  circumstances  reveal  very  different  properties  of 
integrals;  their  study  has  been  delved  into  only  in  a  few  particular 
cases,  and  it  raises  questions  into  which  enter  the  most  profound 
notions  of  modern  analysis. 


I  will  enter  into  certain  analytic  details  especially  interesting  for 
mathematical  physics. 

The  question  of  the  generality  of  the  solution  of  a  partial  differential 
equation  has  presented  some  apparent  paradoxes.  For  the  same 
equation,  the  number  of  arbitrary  functions  figuring  in  the  general 
integral  was  not  always  the  same,  following  the  form  of  the  integral 
envisaged.  Thus  Fourier,  studying  the  equation  of  heat  in  an  indefin- 
ite medium,  considers  as  evident  that  a  solution  will  be  determined 
if  its  value  for  ^  =  0  is  given,  that  is  to  say  one  arbitrary  function  of 
the  three  coordinates  x,  y,  z;  from  the  point  of  view  of  Cauchy,  we 
may  consider,  on  the  contrary,  that  in  the  general  solution  there  are 
two  arbitrary  functions  of  the  three  variables.  In  reality,  the  ques- 
tion, as  it  has  long  been  stated,  has  not  a  precise  signification. 

In  the  first  place,  when  it  is  a  question  only  of  analytic  functions, 
any  finite  number  of  functions  of  any  number  of  independent  vari- 
ables presents,  from  the  arithmetical  point  of  view,  no  greater  gen- 
erality than  a  single  function  of  a  single  variable,  since  in  the  one 
case  and  in  the  other  the  ensemble  of  coefficients  of  the  development 
forms  an  enumerable  series.  But  there  is  something  more.  In  reality, 
beyond  the  conditions  which  are  translated  by  given  functions,  an 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   MATHEMATICAL   ANALYSIS     509 

integral  is  subjected  to  conditions  of  continuity,  or  is  to  become  in- 
finite in  a  determined  manner  for  certain  elements;  one  may  so  be 
led  to  regard  as  equivalent  to  an  arbitrary  function  the  condition 
of  continuity  in  a  given  space,  and  then  we  clearly  see  how  badly 
formulated  is  the  question  of  giving  the  number  of  the  arbitrary 
functions.  It  is  at  times  a  delicate  matter  to  demonstrate  that  con- 
ditions determine  in  a  unique  manner  a  solution,  when  we  do  not 
wish  to  be  contented  with  probabilities;  it  is  then  necessary  to  make 
precise  the  manner  in  which  the  function  and  certain  of  its  deriva- 
tives conduct  themselves. 

Thus  in  Fourier's  problem  relative  to  an  indefinite  medium  cer- 
tain hypotheses  must  be  made  about  the  function  and  its  first 
derivatives  at  infinity,  if  we  wish  to  establish  that  the  solution  is 
unique.  x 

Formulas  analogous  to  Green's  render  great  services,  but  the 
demonstrations  one  deduces  from  them  are  not  always  entirely 
rigorous,  implicitly  supposing  fulfilled  for  the  limits  conditions 
which  are  not,  a  'priori  at  least,  necessary.  This  is,  after  so  many 
others,  a  new  example  of  the  evolution  of  exigencies  in  the  rigor  of 
proofs. 

We  remark,  moreover,  that  the  new  study,  rendered  necessary, 
has  often  led  to  a  better  account  of  the  nature  of  integrals. 

True  rigor  is  fecund,  thus  distinguishing  itself  from  another  purely 
formal  and  tedious,  which  spreads  a  shadow  over  the  problems  it 
touches. 

The  difficulties  in  the  demonstration  of  the  unity  of  a  solution 
may  be  very  different  according  as  it  is  question  of  equations  of 
which  all  the  integrals  are  or  are  not  analytic.  This  is  an  important 
point,  and  shows  that  even  when  we  wish  to  put  them  aside,  it  is 
necessary  sometimes  to  consider  non-analytic  functions. 

Thus  we  cannot  affirm  that  Cauchy's  problem  determines  in  a 
unique  manner  one  solution,  the  data  of  the  problem  being  general, 
that  is  to  say  not  being  characteristic. 

This  is  surely  the  case,  if  we  envisage  only  analytic  integrals, 
but  with  non-analytic  integrals  there  may  be  contacts  of  order 
infinite.  And  theory  here  does  not  outstrip  applications;  on  the 
contrary,  as  the  following  example  shows: 

Does  the  celebrated  theorem  of  Lagrange  on  the  potentials  of 
velocity  in  a  perfect  fiuid  hold  good  in  a  viscid  fluid?  Examples  have 
been  given  where  the-  coordinates  of  different  points  of  a  viscous 
fluid  starting  from  rest  are  not  expressible  as  analytic  functions  of 
the  time  starting  from  the  initial  instant  of  the  motion,  and  where 
the  nul  rotations  as  well  as  all  their  derivatives  with  respect  to  the 
time  at  this  instant  are,  however,  not  identically  nul;  Lagrange's 
theorem,  therefore,  does  not  hold  true. 


510  ALGEBRA   AND   ANALYSIS 

These  considerations  sufficiently  show  the  interest  it  may  have 
to  be  assured  that  all  the  integrals  of  a  system  .of  partial  differential 
equations  continuous  as  well  as  all  their  derivatives  up  to  a  deter- 
mined order  in  a  certain  field  of  real  variables  are  analytic  functions; 
it  is  understood,  we  suppose,  there  are  in  the  equations  only  analytic 
elements.  We  have  for  linear  equations  precise  theorems,  all  the 
integrals  being  analytic,  if  the  characteristics  are  imaginary,  and 
very  general  propositions  have  also  been  obtained  in  other  cases. 
.  The  conditions  at  the  limits  that  one  is  led  to  assume  are  very 
different  according  as  it  is  question  of  an  equation  of  which  the 
integrals  are  or  are  not  analytic.  A  type  of  the  first  case  is  given 
by  the  problem  generalized  by  Dirichlet;  conditions  of  continuity 
there  play  an  essential  part,  and,  in  general,  the  solution  cannot 
be  prolonged  fronv  the  two  sides  of  the  continuum  which  serves  as 
support  to  the  data;  it  is  no  longer  the  same  in  the  second  case, 
where  the  disposition  of  this  support  in  relation  to  the  characteris- 
tics plays  the  principal  role,  and  where  the  field  of  existence  of  the 
solution  presents  itself  under  wholly  different  conditions.  • 

All  these  notions,  difficult  to  make  precise  in  ordinary  language 
and  fundamental  for  mathematical  physics,  are  not  of  less  interest 
for  infinitesimal  geometry. 

It  will  suffice  to  recall  that  all  the  surfaces  of  constant  positive 
curvature  are  analytic,  while  there  exist  surfaces  of  constant  nega- 
tive curvature  not  analytic. 

From  antiquity  has  been  felt  the  confused  sentiment  of  a  certain 
economy  in  natural  phenomena;  one  of  the  first  precise  examples 
is  furnished  by  Format's  principle  relative  to  the  economy  of  time 
in  the  transmission  of  light. 

Then  we  came  to  recognize  that  the  general  equations  of  mechanics 
correspond  to  a  problem  of  minimum,  or  more  exactly  of  variation, 
and  thus  we  obtained  the  principle  of  virtual  velocities,  then  Ham- 
ilton's principle,  and  that  of  least  action.  A  great  number  of  problems 
appeared  then  as  corresponding  to  minima  of  certain  definite  in- 
tegrals. 

This  was  a  very  important  advance,  because  the  existence  of 
a  minimum  could  in  many  cases  be  regarded  as  evident,  and  con- 
sequently the  demonstration  of  the  existence  of  the  solution  was 
effected. 

This  reasoning  has  rendered  immense  services;  the  greatest  geo- 
meters. Gauss  in  the  problem  of  the  distribution  of  an  attracting 
mass  corresponding  to  a  given  potential,  Riemann  in  his  theory  of 
Abelian  functions,  have  been  satisfied  with  it.  To-day  our  attention 
has  been  called  to  the  dangers  of  this  sort  of  demonstration;  it  is 
possible  for  the  minima  to  be  simply  limits  and  not  to  be  actually 
attained  by  veritable  functions  possessing  the  necessary  properties 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS    511 

of  continuity.  We  are,  therefore,  no  longer  content  with  the  prob- 
abilities offered  by  the  reasoning  long  classic. 

Whether  we  proceed  indirectly  or  whether  we  seek  to  give  a  rigor- 
ous proof  of  the  existence  of  a  function  corresponding  to  the  mini- 
mum, the  route  is  long  and  arduous. 

Further,  not  the  less  will  it  be  always  useful  to  connect  a  ques- 
tion of  mechanics  or  of  mathematical  physics  with  a  problem  of 
minimum;  in  this  first  of  all  is  a  source  of  fecund  analytic  trans- 
formations, and  besides  in  the  very  calculations  of  the  investigation 
of  variations  useful  indications  may  appear,  relative  to  the  condi- 
tions at  the  limits;  a  beautiful  example  of  it  was  given  by  Kirchoff 
in  the  delicate  investigation  of  the  conditions  at  the  limits  of  the 
equilibrium  of  flexure  of  plates. 

VI 

I  have  been  led  to  expand  particularly  on  partial  differential 
equations. 

Examples  chosen  in  rational  mechanics  and  in  celestial  mechanics 
would  readily  show  the  role  which  ordinary  differential  equations 
play  in  the  progress  of  these  sciences  whose  history,  as  we  have  seen, 
has  been  so  narrowly  bound  to  that  of  analysis. 

When  the  hope  of  integrating  with  simple  functions  was  lost,  one 
strove  to  find  developments  permitting  to  follow  a  phenomenon  as  long 
as  possible,  or  at  least  to  obtain  information  of  its  qualitative  bearing. 

For  practice,  the  methods  of  approximation  form  an  extremely 
important  part  of  mathematics,  and  it  is  thus  that  the  highest  parts 
of  theoretic  arithmetic  find  themselves  connected  with  the  applied 
sciences.  As  to  series,  the  demonstrations  themselves  of  the  exist- 
ence of  integrals  furnish  them  from  the  very  first;  thus  Cauchy's 
first  method  gives  developments  convergent  as  long  as  the  integrals 
and  the  differential  coefficients  remain  continuous. 

When  any  circumstance  permits  our  foreseeing  that  such  is  always 
the  case,  we  obtain  developments  always  convergent.  In  the  pro- 
blem of  n  bodies,  we  can  in  this  way  obtain  developments  valid  so 
long  as  there  are  no  shocks. 

If  the  bodies,  instead  of  attracting,  repel  each  other,  this  contin- 
gency need  not  be  feared  and  we  should  obtain  developments  valid 
indefinitely;  unhappily,  as  Fresnel  said  one  day  to  Laplace,  nature 
is  not  concerned  about  analytic  difficulties  and  the  celestial  bodies 
attract  instead  of  repelling  each  other. 

One  would  even  be  tempted  at  times  to  go  further  than  the  great 
physicist  and  say  that  nature  has  sown  difficulties  in  the  paths  of 
the  analysts. 

Thus,  to  take  another  example,  we  can  generally  decide,  given  a 
system  of  differential  equations  of  the  first  order,  whether  the  gen- 


512  ALGEBRA  AND   ANALYSIS 

eral  solution  is  stable  or  not  about  a  point,  and  to  find  developments 
in  series  valid  for  stable  solutions  it  is  only  necessary  that  certain 
inequalities  be  verified. 

But  if  we  apply  these  results  to  the  equations  of  dynamics  to  dis- 
cuss stability,  we  find  ourselves  exactly  in  the  particular  case  which 
is  unfavorable.  Nay,  in  general,  here  it  is  not  possible  to  decide  on 
the  stability;  in  the  case  of  a  function  of  forces  having  a  maximum, 
reasoning  classic,  but  indirect,  establishes  the  stability  which  cannot 
be  deduced  from  any  development  valid  for  every  value  of  the  time. 

Do  not  lament  these  difficulties;  they  will  be  the  source  of  future 
progress. 

Such  are  also  the  difficulties  which  still  present  to  us,  in  spite  of 
so  many  works,  the  equations  of  celestial  mechanics;  the  astro- 
nomers have  almost  drawn  from  them,  since  Newton,  by  means  of 
series  practically  convergent  and  approximations  happily  con- 
ducted, all  that  is  necessary  for  the  foretelling  of  the  motions  of  the 
heavenly  bodies. 

Th-e  analysts  would  ask  more,  but  they  no  longer  hope  to  attain 
the  integration  by  means  of  simple  functions  or  developments  al- 
ways convergent. 

What  admirable  recent  researches  have  best  taught  them  is  the 
immense  difficulty  of  the  problem;  a  new  way  has,  however,  been 
opened  by  the  study  of  particular  solutions,  such  as  the  periodic 
solutions  and  the  asymptotic  solutions  which  have  already  been 
utilized.  It  is  not  perhaps  so  much  because  of  the  needs  of  practice 
as  in  order  not  to  avow  itself  vanquished,  that  analysis  will  never 
resign  itself  to  abandon,  without  a  decisive  victory,  a  subject  where 
it  has  met  so  many  brilliant  triumphs;  and  again,  what  more  beau- 
tiful field  could  the  theories  new-born  or  rejuvenated  of  the  modern 
doctrine  of  functions  find,  to  essay  their  forces,  than  this  classic 
problem  of  n  bodies? 

It  is  a  joy  for  the  analyst  to  encounter  in  applications  equations 
that  he  can  integrate  with  known  functions,  with  transcendents 
already  classed. 

Such  encounters  are  unhapily  rare;  the  problem  of  the  pendulum, 
the  classic  cases  of  the  motion  of  a  solid  body  around  a  fixed  point, 
are  examples  where  the  elliptic  functions  have  permitted  us  to  effect 
the  integration. 

It  would  also  be  extremely  interesting  to  encounter  a  question 
of  mechanics  which  might  be  the  origin  of  the  discovery  of  a  new 
transcendent  possessing  some  remarkable  property;  I  should  be 
embarrassed  to  give  an  example  of  it  unless  in  carrying  back  to  the 
pendulum  the  debut  of  the  theory  of  elliptic  functions. 

The  interpenetration  between  theory  and  applications  is  here 
much  less  than  in  the  questions  of  mathematical  physics.     Thus 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS    513 

is  explained  that,  since  forty  years,  the  works  on  ordinary  differ- 
ential equations  attached  to  analytic  functions  have  had  in  great 
part  a  theoretic  character  altogether  abstract. 

The  pure  theory  has  notably  taken  the  advance;  we  have  had 
occasion  to  say  that  it  was  well  it  should  be  so,  but  evidently  there 
is  here  a  question  of  measure,  and  we  may  hope  to  see  the  old  pro- 
blems profit  by  the  progress  accomplished. 

It  would  not  be  over-difficult  to  give  some  examples,  and  I  will  re- 
call only  those  linear  differential  equations,  where  figure  arbitrary 
parameters  whose  singular  values  are  roots  of  entire  transcendent 
functions ;  which  in  particular  makes  the  successive  harmonics  of 
a  vibrating  membrane  correspond  to  the  poles  of  a  meromorphic 
function. 

It  happens  also  that  the  theory  may  be  an  element  of  classifica- 
tion in  leading  to  seek  conditions  for  which  the  solution  falls  under 
a  determined  type,  as  for  example  that  the  integral  may  be  uniform. 
There  have  been  and  there  yet  will  be  many  interesting  discoveries 
in  this  way,  the  case  of  the  motion  of  a  solid  heavy  body  treated 
by  Madame  de  Kovalevski  and  where  the  Abelian  functions  were 
utilized  is  a  remarkable  example. 

VII 

In  studying  the  reciprocal  relations  of  analysis  with  mechanics 
and  mathematical  physics,  we  have  on  our  way  more  than  once 
encountered  the  infinitesimal  geometry,  which  has  proposed  so 
many  celebrated  problems;  in  many  difficult  questions,  the  happy 
combination  of  calculus  and  synthetic  reasonings  has  realized  con- 
siderable progress,  as  is  shown  by  the  theories  of  applicable  surfaces 
and  systems  triply  orthogonal. 

It  is  another  part  of  geometry  which  plays  a  grand  role  in  certain 
analytic  researches,  I  mean  the  geometry  of  situation  or  analysis 
situs.  We  know  that  Riemann  made  from  this  point  of  view  a  com- 
plete study  of  the  continuum  of  two  dimensions,  on  which  rests  his 
theory  of  algebraic  functions  and  their  integrals. 

When  this  number  of  dimensions  augments,  the  questions  of 
analysis  situs  become  necessarily  complicated;  the  geometric  intui- 
tion ceases,  and  the  study  becomes  purely  analytic,  the  mind  being 
guided  solely  by  analogies  which  may  be  misleading  and  need  to  be 
discussed  very  closely.  The  theory  of  algebraic  functions  of  two 
variables,  which  transports  us  into  a  space  of  four  dimensions, 
without  getting  from  -analysis  situs  an  aid  so  fruitful  as  does  the 
theory  of  functions  of  one  variable,  owes  it,  however,  useful  orient- 
ations. 

There  is  also  another  order  of  questions  where  the  geometry  of 
situation  intervenes;  in  the  study  of  curves  traced  on  a  surface  and 


514  ALGEBRA   AND  ANALYSIS 

defined  by  differential  equations,  the  connection  of  this  surface  plays 
an  important  role;  this  happens  for  geodesic  lines. 

The  notion  of  connexity,  moreover,  presented  itself  long  ago  in 
analysis,  when  the  study  of  electric  currents  and  magnetism  led 
to  non-uniform  potentials;  in  a  more  general  manner  certain  multi- 
form integrals  of  some  partial ,  differential  equations  are  met  in 
difficult  theories,  such  as  that  of  diffraction,  and  varied  researches 
must  continue  in  this  direction. 

From  a  different  point  of  view,  I  must  yet  recall  the  relations  of 
algebraic  analysis  with  geometry,  which  manifest  themselves  so 
elegantly  in  the  theory  of  groups  of  finite  order. 

A  regular  polyhedron,  say  an  icosahedron,  is  on  the  one  hand  the 
solid  that  all  the  world  knows;  it  is  also,  for  the  analyst,  a  group  of 
finite  order,  corresponding  to  the  divers  ways  of  making  the  poly- 
hedron coincide  with  itself. 

The  investigation  of  all  the  types  of  groups  of  motion  of  finite 
order  interests  not  alone  the  geometers,  but  also  the  crystallo- 
graphers;  it  goes  back  essentially  to  the  study  of  groups  of  ternary 
linear-  substitutions  of  determinant  +1,  and  leads  to  the  thirty- 
two  systems  of  symmetry  of  the  crystal  lographers  for  the  particular 
complex. 

The  grouping  in  systems  of  polyhedra  corresponding  so  as  to  fill 
space  exhausts  all  the  possibilities  in  the  investigation  of  the  struc- 
ture of  crystals. 

Since  the  epoch  when  the  notion  of  group  was  introduced  into 
algebra  by  Galois,  it  has  taken,  in  divers  ways,  considerable  devel- 
opment, so  that  to-day  it  is  met  in  all  parts  of  mathematics.  In  the 
applications,  it  appears  to  us  above  all  as  an  admirable  instrument 
of  classification.  Whether  it  is  a  question  of  substitution  groups 
or  of  Sophus  Lie's  transformation  groups,  whether  it  is  a  question 
of  algebraic  equations  or  of  differential  equations,  this  comprehen- 
sive doctrine  permits  explanation  of  the  degree  of  difficulty  of  the 
problems  treated  and  teaches  how  to  utilize  the  special  circumstances 
which  present  themselves;  thus  it  should  interest  as  well  mechanics 
and  mathematical  physics  as  pure  analysis. 

The  degree  of  development  of  mechanics  and  physics  has  per- 
mitted giving  to  almost  all  their  theories  a  mathematical  form; 
certain  hypotheses,  the  knowledge  of  elementary  laws,  have  led 
to  differential  relations  which  constitute  the  last  form  under  which 
these  theories  settle  down,  at  least  for  a  time.  These  latter  have 
seen  little  by  little  their  field  enlarge  with  the  principles  of  thermo- 
dynamics; to-day  chemistry  tends  to  take  in  its  turn  a  mathemat- 
ical form. 

I  will  take  as  witness  of  it  only  the  celebrated  memoir  of  Gibbs 
on  the  equilibrium  of  chemical  systems,  so  analytic  in  character, 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  MATHEMATICAL   ANALYSIS     515 

and  where  it  needed  some  effort  on  the  part  of  the  chemists  to 
recognize,  under  their  algebraic  mantle,  laws  of  high  importance. 

It  seems  that  chemistry  has  to-day  gotten  out  of  the  premathe- 
matic  period,  by  which  every  science  begins,  and  that  a  day  must 
come  when  will  be  systematized  grand  theories,  analogous  to  those 
of  our  present  mathematical  physics,  but  far  more  vast,  and  com- 
prising the  ensemble  of  physicochemic  phenomena. 

It  would  be  premature  to  ask  if  analysis  will  find  in  their  develop- 
ments the  source  of  new  progress;  we  do  not  even  know  before- 
hand what  analytic  types  one  might  find. 

I  haA^e  constantly  spoken  of  differential  equations  ruling  phe- 
nomena; will  this  always  be  the  final  form  which  condenses  a  theory? 
Of  this  I  know  nothing  certain,  but  we  should,  however,  remember 
that  many  hypotheses  have  been  made  of  more  or  less  experimental 
nature ;  among  them,  one  is  what  has  been  called  the  principle  of 
non-heredity,  which  postulates  that  the  future  of  a  system  depends 
only  on  its  present  state  and  its  state  at  an  instant  infinitely  near, 
or,  more  briefly,  that  accelerations  depend  only  on  positions  and 
velocities. 

We  know  that  in  certain  cases  this  hypothesis  is  not  admissible, 
at  least  with  the  magnitudes  directly  envisaged;  one  has  sometimes 
misemployed  on  this  subject  the  memory  of  matter,  which  recalls 
its  past,  and  has  spoken  in  affected  terms  of  the  life  of  a  morsel  of 
steel.  Different  attempts  have  been  made  to  give  a  theor}^  of  these 
phenomena,  where  a  distant  past  seems  to  interfere;  of  them  I  need 
not  speak  here.  An  analyst  may  think  that  in  cases  so  complex  it 
is  necessary  to  abandon  the  form  of  differential  equations,  and  resign 
one's  self  to  envisage  functional  equations,  where  figure  definite 
integrals  which  will  be  the  witness  of  a  sort  of  heredity. 

To  see  the  interest  which  is  attached  at  this  moment  to  functional 
equations,  one  might  believe  in  a  presentiment  of  the  future  needs 
of  science. 

VIII 

After  having  spoken  of  non-heredity,  I  scarcely  dare  touch  the 
question  of  the  applications  of  analysis  to  biology. 

It  will  be  some  time,  no  doubt,  before  one  forms  the  functional 
equations  of  biologic  phenomena;  the  attempts  so  far  made  are 
in  a  very  modest  order  of  ideas;  yet  efforts  are  being  made  to  get 
out  of  the  purely  qualitative  field,  to  introduce  quantitative  meas- 
ures. In  the  question  of  the  variation  of  certain  characteristics, 
mensuration  has  been  engaged  in,  and  statistic  measures  which  are 
translated  by  curves  of  frequency.  The  modifications  of  these  curves 
with  successive  generations,  their  decompositions  into  distinct  curves, 
may  give  the  measure  of  the  stability  of  species  or  of  the  rapidity 


516  ALGEBRA   AND   ANALYSIS 

of  mutations,  and  we  know  what  interest  attaches  itself  to  these 
questions  in  recent  botanic  researches.  In  all  this  so  great  is  the 
number  of  parameters  that  one  questions  whether  the  infinitesimal 
method  itself  could  be  of  any  service.  Some  laws  of  a  simple  arith- 
metic character  like  those  of  Mendel  come  occasionally  to  give 
renewed  confidence  in  the  old  aphorism  which  I  cited  in  the  begin- 
ning, that  all  things  are  explained  by  numbers;  but,  in  spite  of 
legitimate  hopes,  it  is  clear  that,  in  its  totality,  biology  is  still  far 
from  entering  upon  a  period  truly  mathematical. 

It  is  not  so,  according  to  certain  economists,  with  potential  econ- 
omy. After  Cournot,  the  Lausanne  school  made  an  effort  extremely 
interesting  to  introduce  mathematical  analysis  into  political  econ- 
omy. 

Under  certain  hypotheses,  which  fit  at  least  limiting  cases,  we 
find  in  learned  treatises  an  equation  between  the  quantities  of 
merchandise  and  their  prices,  which  recalls  the  equation  of  virtual 
velocities  in  mechanics:  this  is  the  equation  of  economic  equilib- 
rium. A  function  of  quantities  plays  in  this  theory  an  essential  role 
recalling  that  of  the  potential  function.  Moreover,  the  best  author- 
ized representatives  of  the  school  insist  on  the  analogy  of  economic 
phenomena  with  mechanical  phenomena.  "As  rational  mechanics," 
says  one  of  them,  "■  considers  material  points,  pure  economy  con- 
siders the  homo  oeconomicus." 

Naturally,  we  find  there  also  the  analogues  of  Lagrange's  equa- 
tions, indispensable  matrix  of  all  mechanics. 

While  admiring  these  bold  works,  we  fear  lest  the  authors  have 
neglected  certain  hidden  masses,  as  Helmholtz  and  Hertz  would 
have  said.  But  although  that  may  happen,  there  is  in  these  doctrines 
a  curious  application  of  mathematics,  which,  at  least,  in  well-circum- 
scribed cases,  has  already  rendered  great  services. 

I  have  terminated,  messieurs,  this  summary  history  of  some  of 
the  applications  of  analysis,  with  the  reflections  which  it  has  at 
moments  suggested  to  me.  It  is  far  from  being  complete;  thus  I  have 
omitted  to  speak  of  the  calculus  of  probabilities,  which  demands 
so  much  subtlety  of  mind,  and  of  which  Pascal  refused  to  explain  the 
niceties  to  the  Chevalier  de  Mere  because  he  was  not  a  geometer. 

Its  practical  utility  is  of  the  first  rank,  its  theoretic  interest  has 
always  been  great;  it  is  further  augmented  to-day,  thanks  to  the 
importance  taken  by  the  researches  that  Maxwell  called  statistical 
and  which  tend  to  envisage  mechanics  under  a  wholly  new  light. 

I  hope,  however,  to  have  shown,  in  this  sketch,  the  origin  and 
the  reason  of  the  bonds  so  profound  which  unite  analysis  to  geometry 
and  physics,  more  generally  to  every  science  bearing  on  quantities 
numerically  measurable. 


DEVELOPMENT   OF   MATHEMATICAL   ANALYSIS     517 

The  reciprocal  influence  of  analysis  and  physical  theories  has  been 
in  this  regard  particularly  instructive. 

What  does  the  future  hold? 

Problems  more  difficult,  corresponding  to  an  approximation  of 
higher  order,  will  introduce  complications  which  we  can  only  vaguely 
forecast,  in  speaking,  as  I  have  just  done,  of  functional  equations 
replacing  systematically  our  actual  differential  equations,  or  further 
of  integrations  of  equations  infinite  in  number  with  an  infinity  of 
unknowTi  functions.  But  even  though  that  happens,  mathematical 
analysis  will  always  remain  that  language  which,  according  to  the 
mot  of  Fourier,  has  no  symbols  to  express  confused  notions,  a  lan- 
guage endowed  with  an  admirable  power  of  transformation  and 
capable  of  condensing  in  its  formulas  an  immense  number  of  results. 


ON  PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS 

BY  HEINEICH    MASCHKE 

[Heinrich  Maschke,  Associate  Professor  of  Mathematics,  University  of 
Chicago,  b.  Breslau,  Germany,  October  24,  1853.  A.B.  Magdalenen  Gym- 
nasium, Breslau,  1872;  Ph.D.  Gottingen,  1880.  Post-graduate  Heidelberg, 
Breslau,  Berlin,  and  Gottingen.  Professor  Mathematics  Lvisenstadt.  Gym- 
nasium, Berlin,  1880-90;  Electric  Engineer  at  Weston  Electric  Company, 
Newark,  New  Jersey,  1890-92;  Assistant  Professor  of  Mathematics,  Uni- 
versity of  Chicago,  1892-96.] 

As  set  forth  by  the  Committee  directing  the  affairs  of  this  Interna- 
tional Congress,  the  address  which  I  have  the  distinguished  privilege 
of  delivering  to-day  shall  be  on  "Present  Problems  in  Algebra  and 
Analysis,"  —  but  it  is  not  provided  by  the  Committee  how  many 
of  these  problems  shall  be  treated. 

The  different  branches  of  algebra  and  analysis  which  have  been 
investigated  are  so  numerous  that  it  would  be  quite  impossible  to 
give  an  approximately  exhaustive  representation  even  only  of  the 
most  important  problems,  within  the  limits  of  the  time  allowed  to 
me.  I,  therefore,  have  confined  myself  to  the  minimum  admissible 
number,  namely  one,  or  rather  one  group  of  problems. 

Of  this  one  problem,  however,  this  Section  of  Algebra  and  Analysis 
has  the  right  to  expect  that  it  is  neither  purely  algebraic  nor  purely 
analytic,  but  one  which  touches  both  fields;  and  at  least  in  this 
respect  I  hope  that  my  selection  has  been  fortunate. 

I  purpose  to  speak  to-day  on  the  Theory  of  Invariants  of  Quad- 
ratic Differential  Quantics.  Invariants  suggest  at  once  algebra, 
differential  quantics:  analysis.  At  the  same  time  the  subject  also 
leads  into  geometry,  —  it  contains,  for  instance,  a  great  part  of 
differential  geometry  and  of  geometry  of  hyperspace.  But  is  there, 
indeed,  any  algebraic  or  analytic  problem  which  does  not  allow 
geometrical  interpretation  in  some  way  or  other?  And  when  it  comes 
to  geometry  of  hyperspace,  —  it  is  then  only  geometrical  language 
that  we  are  using,  —  what  we  are  actually  considering  are  analytic 
or  algebraic  forms.  Moreover,  rigorous  definitions  and  discussions 
of  geometrical  propositions  of  an  invariant  character  in  particular 
can  only  be  given  by  tracing  them  back  to  their  analytic  origin. 

In  the  following  exposition  I  shall  first  speak  on  the  various  in- 
variant expressions  of  differential  quadratics  as  they  occur  in  geo- 
metry of  two  and  more  dimensions,  and  then  take  up  the  purely 
analytic  representation  in  the  second  part  of  the  paper. 

This  corresponds  also  to  the  historical  development  of  the  sub- 


PROBLEMS  OF  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS    519 

ject:  geometry  has  here  as  well  as  in  many  other  branches  of  mathe- 
matics indicated  the  problems  which  in  their  later  development 
turned  out  to  be  of  paramount  interest  in  pure  analysis. 

A  few  preliminary  remarks  concerning  the  nomenclature  of  the 
different  types  of  invariant  expressions  will  be  necessary. 

To  a  given  differential  quadratic  form 

n 

•  A=  ^  aikdxidxk,iO'ki=aik) 

where  the  a^^'s  are  functions  of  the  n  independent  variables  Xi,  x^,  .  .  . 
Xn,  we  apply  a  general  point  transformation  of  the  variables  x, 

Xi=Xi(y^,y„  .  .  .  Vn). 
We  observe  that  the  differentials  dx  are  then  transformed  into 
linear  expressions  of  the  differentials  dy  with  the  Jacobian  of  the 
x's  with  respect  to  the  y's  as  the  substitution-determinant  which 
we  shall  call  r. 

By  this  transformation  A  goes  into 

A'=Ia'ikdyidyk. 

Let  now  <?  be  a  function 

(a)  of  the  coefficients  aik  and  their  first,  second,  .  .  .  derivatives, 

(b)  of  U,  V,  .  .  .  and  their  derivatives,  where  U,  V,  .  .  .  are  any 
arbitrary  functions  of  Xj,  3:2,  .  .  .  x„. 

If  then  0  remains  the  same  whether  formed  for  the  new  or  for 
the  old  quantities,  that  is,  if 

0(a\,,  ^,  .  .  .  ,  t/^i^,  ...,r,...)  =0(a,,,  ^-^,...,U,^JL, 
dyk  dyX  dxX  dx), 

...y, ...)    _ 

we  say  that  0  is  an  invariant  (in  the  wider  sense)  of  A. 

If  0  contains  only  the  a^^'s  and  their  derivatives,  we  call  it  an 
invariant  proper,  and  its  order  the  order  of  the  highest  derivative 
occurring  in  it.  If  0  contains  also  one  or  more  arbitrary  functions 
U,V,  ...  we  call  it  a  differential  parameter,  the  definition  of  order 
being  the  same  as  before. 
*  If  more  than  one  differential  quadratic  is  given  it  is  easily  under- 
stood what  is  meant  by  simultaneous  invariants  and  simultaneous 
differential  parameters. 

In  strict  analogy  with  the  algebraic  theory  of  invariants  we  call 
covariants  expressions  0  of  the  above  invariantive  nature,  provided 
that  we  also  allow  the  differentials  dx  to  enter  into  0. 

The  first  and  the  most  important  example  of  a  differential  quad- 
ratic quantic  is  the  square  of  the  arc-element  on  a  surface 

ds^  =Edu^  +2Fdudv  +  Gdv\ 
It    was  Gauss    who  made   (1827),  in    his    Disquisitiones    generales 
circa  superficies  curvas,  this  expression  the  fundamental  object  of 


520 


ALGEBRA   AND  ANALYSIS 


investigation.    He  also  gave,  in  what  has  been  called  after  him  the 

Gaussian  Curvature 

dE  . 

K  =  (E,F,G,—->-  '  •), 
ou 

the  first  example  of   an  invariant.     Gauss  defines  this  curvature 
geometrically  and  finds  for  it  the  analytic  expression 

LN-M^ 

EG-F^ 

which  is  a  simultaneous  invariant  of  two  differential  quantics, 

namely,  of  ds^  and  of—  =Ldu'^+2Mdudv-]-Ndv^. 


This  shows  that  K  is  independent  of  the  M,'y-system  on  the 
surface.  And  now  Gauss  expresses  K  in  terms  of  E,  F,  G  and  the 
first  and  second  derivatives  of  these  quantities  alone.  A  direct 
demonstration  that  K  is  an  invariant  proper  of  the  differential 
quantic  ds^  alone,  —  that  is,  without  passing   through  the  second 

ds^  .       , 

differential  quantic  — ,  —  is  of  course  desirable.^     Each  one  of  the 
P 

general  methods  of  treating  the  theory  of  invariants,  which  will  be 

discussed  in  the  latter  part  of  this  paper,  furnishes  such  a  direct 

proof.    In  particular,  the  aspect  of  the  formula  for  K,  on  p.  528, 

deduced  by  the  symbolic  method,  shows  immediately  the  invariant 

character  of  K. 

Differential  parameters  were  introduced  into  differential  geometry 

by  Beltrami  in  1863.   These  are  the  well-known  expressions 


J^Cp: 


\dvj  du  dv        \duj 


EG-F^ 


F{^,4>)  = 


dv  dv  \du  dv      dv  duj         du  du 


EG-F^ 


J2(P  = 


1 


Veg-f^ 


du        dv 
\/E~G^P 


+ 


dv 


E 


dip         dip 


dv 


F 


du 


\/EG-F^ 


where  ip  and  0  are  the  arbitrary  functions  which  take  the  place  of 
U ,  V  in  our  general  definition  of  differential  parameters.  Beltrami 
adopted  the  name  "  differential  parameters  "  and  also  the  notation 

I  Cf .  on  this  subject  the  interesting  paper  by  Knoblauch :  "  Der  Gauss'sche  Satz 
vom  Kriimmungsmass,"  Sitzungsberichte  der  Berliner  Mathem.  Gesellschaft.  April 
27, 1904. 


PROBLEMS  OF  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS    521 

J  from  Lame,  who,  in  his  Lecons  sur  les  coordonnees  curvilignes, 
defined  in  1859  his  differential  parameters 

d^(p       d'^cp        d^<p 

for  the  three-dimensional  case  where  the  arc-element  is  of  the  form 

ds^^dx^  +dy^  ■\-dz'^. 

Lame  recognized  the  fundamental  importance  of  these  quantities 
and  made  a  systematical  use  of  them  on  account  of  their  invariance 
with  respect  to  any  point-transformation  preserving  the  form  ds"^. 

The  general  theory  of  invariants  defines  the  differential  parameters 
J,  and  Jj  for  the  case  of  n  variables.  From  these  general  expressions 
Beltrami's  differential  parameters  are  directly  obtained  for  n  =  2, 
Lame's  quantities  (Ji)^  and  Jj  for  the  special  form  of  ds'^  in  the  case 
n=3. 

The  number  of  differential  parameters  is  of  course  infinite,  but 

Darboux  in  his  Lecons  sur  la  theorie  generale  des  surfaces  has  proved 

that  all  of  them  are  expressible  by  means  of  ij,  J.^,  f  and  the  evident 

differential  parameter 

dip  dij)     dip  dip 

du  dv     dv  du 
6(0, (p)  = ==_ — 

(by  forming,  for  instance,  Ji(J^(p)  etc.)  —  an  important  theorem 
which  has  later  been  extended  by  Staeckel  to  an  analogous  theorem 
for  the  case  of  n  variables. 

The  expression  Jicp  occurs  already  in  Gauss's  Disquisitiones . 
By  taking  as  parameter  curves  a  singly  infinite  system  of  geodesies 
and  its  orthogonal  trajectories  he  transforms  the  arc-element  into 
the  form 

ds^  =dr^ -\-w?d(p'^ 
and  shows  that  r  satisfies  the  differential  equation 

A,r  =  \. 

An  important  differential  parameter  is  the  geodesic  curvature. 
Its  expression  was  thrown  by  Bonnet  into  a  form  which  is  easily 
recognized  as  a  differential  parameter  (of  the  second  order).  Its 
numerator  =0  represents  the  differential  equation  of  geodesic  lines 
in  an  invariant  form. 

Since  a  transformation  of  the  two  independent  variables  u,  v  which 
preserves  the  same  value  of  ds"^  can  also  be  considered  as  a  transfor- 
mation of  two  surfaces  which  are  applicable  to  each  other,  it  follows 
that  all  invariants  of  ds^  are  also  invariants  of  a  surface  with  respect 
to  the  process  of  bending.    From  this  reason  these  invariants  have 


522  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS 

been  called  by  Weingarten  and  Knoblauch,  who  were  among  the  first 
writers  emphasizing  and  developing  to  a  certain  extent  the  invari- 
antive  side  of  differential  geometry,  in  the  case  of  invariants  proper, 
"  Biegungsinvarianten,"  in  the  case  of  differential  parameters,  "  Bie- 
gungscovarianten,"  and  this  notation  has  been  more  or  less  generally 
adopted.  The  notation  "  Biegungscovarianten "  does  not  agree  with 
the  definition  of  a  covariant  given  above,  but  a  differential  para- 
meter of  ds^  can  easily  be  modified  into  a  covariantive  form  by 
replacing  according  to  the  differential  equation  of  the  curve 

U{u.,v)  =  const. 

oU         dU 
the  derivatives  —  and  -—  by  /idv  and  —  fidu. 
OU  ov 

A  surface  is  completely  defined,  apart  from  its  location  in  space, 
when  in  addition  to  the  quadratic  form  ds^  also 

ds^ 

—  =^Ldu^+2Mdudv+Ndv'' 
P 

is  given,  where  p  denotes  the  radius  of  curvature  along  ds,  —  a  the- 
orem which  was  proved  (1867)  by  Bonnet. 

With  these  two  differential  quantics  given,  we  can  now  at  once 
form  simultaneous  invariants  and  differential  parameters.  The  six 
coefficients,  E,  F,  G,  L,  M,  N  are,  however,  not  independent;  they 
are  related  by  three  partial  differential  equations,  —  the  Gaussian 
relation  and  the  two  Codazzi-Mainardi  equations.  These  three 
relations  are  expressible  in  an  invariantive  form.  The  Gaussian  re- 
lation is 

LN-M^     ^^  ^^  dE 

while  the  two  Codazzi  formulas  are  given  by  the  identical  vanishing 
of  one  simultaneous  linear  covariant. 

As  examples  of  simultaneous  differential  parameters  and  covariants 
I  mention  the  expressions  which,  when  set  equal  to  zero,  represent 
the  differential  equations  of  conjugate  lines,  asymptotic  lines,  and 
lines  of  curvature.  The  differential  equation  of  lines  of  curvature,  for 
instance,  if  written  in  terms  of  du,  dv  represents  a  linear  simultaneous 
covariant;   if  written  as  a  partial  differential  equation  derived  from 

U(u,v)  =  const. 
it  represents  a  simultaneous  differential  parameter  involving  the 
arbitrary  function  U.  The  differential  equation  of  conjugate  lines, 
if  written  in  two  sets  of  differentials  du,  dv  and  du,  dv  represents 
a  bilinear  simultaneous  covariant;  if  written  as  a  partial  differential 
equation  it  represents  a  differential  parameter  involving  two  arbi- 
trary functions  U  and  V. 

The  theory  of  invariants  of  the  above  two  differential  quadratics. 


PROBLEMS  OF  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS    523 

together  with  the  condition  of  the  vanishing  of  one  simultaneous 
invariant  proper  and  one  simultaneous  covariant,  dominates  then, 
in  a  certain  sense,  the  whole  of  differential  geometry. 

Passing  now  to  the  case  of  n  variables  we  may  consider  the  differ- 
ential quadratic  form 

n 

^aikdxidxk^ds^ 

as  the  square  of  the  arc  in  a  hyperspace  of  n  dimensions. 

The  fundamental  role  which  the  Gaussian  curvature  plays  in  the 
case  n=2  is  here  represented  by  an  invariant  expresson  of  ds^  which 
—  in  a  certain  sense  —  might  be  regarded  as  a  generalization  of  the 
Gaussian  curvature,  namely,  the  Riemann  curvature  of  the  hyper- 
space. Riemann's  investigations  on  this  subject  are  found  in  his 
paper,  Ueber  die  Hypothesen,  welche  der  Geometrie  zu  Grunde  liegen, 
and  in  the  mathematical  supplement  to  it  Commentatio  mathematica, 
etc.  in  the  prize-problem  of  the  Parisian  Academy,  1861. 

The  geometrical  definition  of  the  Riemann  curvature  is  briefly  the 
following:  Starting  from  any  point  P  with  the  coordinates  Xi  we 
consider  two  linear  directions  defined  by  the  increments  dxi  and  dxi. 
If  we  remain  in  the  vicinity  of  P  these  two  directions  define  a  plane 
of  two  dimensions  and  the  determinants 

dxidxk  —  dxkdxi 
may  be  considered  as  the  coordinates  of  this  plane.  If  now  we 
draw  geodesic  lines  from  the  point  P  whose  initial  arc-elements 
lie  all  in  this  plane,  then  these  geodesies  define  a  surface  of  two  di- 
mensions and  the  Gaussian  curvature  of  this  geodesic  surface  at  the 
point  P  is  the  Riemann  curvature.    The  analytic  expression  for  it  is 


R=-h 


I  iikrs)  {dx^dXg  —  dx^dx^)  (dxj^dx^.  —  dx^oxk) 
^  lia^tfii^^  -  a^^aj  (dx^dx,  -  dx^dx^)  {dxj^dx^  -  dx^dx,^, 


where  the  sum  is  to  be  taken  over  all  values  of  i,  k,  r,  s  from  1  to  n 
with  the  exception  of  those  for  which  i  =k  or  r  =  s. 

The  coefficients  {ikrs)  are  certain  quantities  depending  on  the 
coefficients  a^-,  their  first  and  second  derivatives;  they  occur  in  the 
literature  mostly  under  the  name  of  the  "  Christoffel  quadruple  index 
symbols."  A  better,  certainly  shorter,  notation  would  be  the  one 
used  by  Ricci,  namely,  "  Riemann  symbols." 

The  Riemann  curvature  R  is  an  invariant  expression,  and  as  its 
form  shows  it  is  a  covariant  of  two  sets  of  differentials.  For  n=2 
it  is  identical  with  the  Gaussian  curvature.  For  greater  numbers 
n  the  value  of  R  depends,  at  a  given  point,  on  the  plane-direction 
at  that  point  and  in  general  varies  with  the  plane.  If  it  should  be 
constant  for  all  plane-directions  through  one  point,  and  if  this  is 
so  for  all  the  points,  then  R  is,  as  Schur  has  shown,  altogether  con- 
stant that  is,  for  every  point. 


524  ALGEBRA    AND   ANALYSIS 

Spaces  of  constant  Riemann  curvature  have  been  the  object  of 
numerous  interesting  investigations^  but  these  are  more  or  less  of 
a  specific  geometric  character. 

If  in  particular  R  is  zero,  then  all  the  Riemann  symbols  vanish 
and  it  can  easily  be  shown  that  ds"^  can  be  transformed  into  the 
sum  of  n  squares 

ds^=^dy\ 
1=1 

The  converse  is  true.    In  this  case  the  hyperspace  of  n  dimensions 

is  called  a  flat  or  also  Euclidean  space. 

In  every  case  the  quadratic 


can  be  transformed  into 


^aikdxidxk 

iA'=l 


8  =  1 

where  r  has  the  maximum  value  '-^^^^|=^-  We  might  say  then  that  the 
given  hyperspace  of  n  dimensions  is  always  contained  in  an 
Euclidean  space  of  n+r  dimensions,  where  r  is  one  of  the  numbers, 

f.     1  n{n—l) 

The  number  r  is  evidently  characteristic  for  the  hyperspace  the 
square  of  the  arc-element  of  which  is  the  given  quadratic.  This 
number  r  has  been  called  by  Ricci  the  class  of  the  given  differential 
quadratic  quantic.  It  is  evident  that  this  class  is  an  invariant  num- 
ber, and  the  condition  that  a  given  differential  quadratic  be  of  class 
r  must  certainly  be  an  invariantive  condition.  For  r  =  0  we  have 
just  seen  that  the  condition  is  R=0.  For  higher  values  of  r  no  at- 
tempt has  yet  been  made,  so  far  as  I  know,  to  establish  this  invari- 
antive condition  though  this  problem  is  certainly  one  of  fundamental 
interest. 

Beltrami,  in  his  paper,  Teoria  generale  dei  parametri  differenziali, 
has  extended  the  definition  of  his  differential  parameters  to  the 
case  of  n  variables.  The  definition,  for  instance,  of  the  first  differ- 
ential parameters  is 

"t,A=l  dXi    dXk 

where  Aik  denotes  the  minor  of  the  element  aik  in  the  determinant 

Wik]    =0" 

Beltrami  shows  that  by  means  of  the  geodesies  emanating  from  one 
point  and  of  the  hypersurfaces  orthogonal  to  them  he  can  choose 
his  parameters  such  that  ds"^  is  transformed  into 

n-l 

ds'^=dr'^-\-  ^  hijcdyidyk, 
t,t=i 

where  r  satisfies  the  equation  Aj-  =  1,  and  that  thus  Gauss's  theorems 


PROBLEMS  OF  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS    525 

on  geodesic  polar  co5rdinates  for  n  =  2  admit  a  perfect  analogon 
in  hyperspace.  Also  in  hyperspace  then  the  determination  of  systems 
of  geodesies  amounts  to  the  integration  of  the  partial  differential 
equation 

This  leads  now  to  the  application  of  differential  quadratics  to 
analytic  mechanics.  If  we  write  down  the  expression  of  the  vis 
viva  of  a  (holonomous)  material  system  in  terms  of  generalized 
coordinates  q^,  q^,  •  •  -qn 

dt     dt 

we  have  at  once  in 

2Tdt''=ds'' 
a  differential  quadratic  before  us. 

If  no  external  forces  act  on  the  system,  then  a  geodesic  line  of  ds^ 
represents  at  once,  as  also  Beltrami  has  shown,  a  path  of  the  sys- 
tem. Thus  the  mechanical  problem  is  practically  reduced  to  the 
integration  of  the  equation  A^(p  =  \. 

In  the  case  of  the  existence  of  external  forces  having  a  potential 
U ,  the  above  differential  quantic  has  to  be  replaced  by 

I{U  -\-h)aikdqidqk 
and  the  mechanical  problem  is  equivalent  to  the  integration  of  the 
equation 

Ji(p  =  U+h 
where  Ji(p  is  the  differential  parameter  of  the  quadratic  form  de- 
noted before  by  ds^. 

A  detailed  exposition  of  the  above-mentioned  researches  of  Bel- 
trami, as  well  as  this  application  to  mechanics,  is  given  in  the  second 
volume  of  Darboux's  Lecons  sur  la  theorie  des  surfaces. 

Passing  now  to  the  second  part  of  my  address,  the  purely  ana- 
lytic theory  of  invariants  of  differential  quadratics,  I  have  first 
to  discuss  that  paper  which  forms  the  foundation  of  almost  all 
later  literature  on  the  subject:  Christoffel's  article  in  Crelle's  Jour- 
nal, vol.  Lxx  (1870),  "Ueber  die  Transformation  der  homogenen 
Differentialausdriicke  des  zweiten  Grades." 

Christoffel  puts  his  problem  in  this  form:  Given  two  differential 
quadratics 

A  =  I aijtdxidxk  and  A'  ^la'  ikdyidyk, 

what  are  the  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  the  equivalence 
of  the  two  quadratics,  that  is,  for  the  existence  of  a  transformation 
of  one  quantic  into  the  other;  and  if  these  conditions  are  established 
how  can  the  required  transformation  be  determined?  (I  should  men- 
tion that  Lame  in  his  already  quoted  work,  Lecons  sur  les  co'dr- 


526  ALGEBRA   AND  ANALYSIS 

donnees  curvilignes,  treats  and  solves  the  analogous  problem  for  the 
case  A=dx^-\-dy^+dz'^). 

Since  the  differentials  dx  are  substituted  linearly  in  terms  of  the 
dy  there  exists  one  and  only  one  algebraic  condition  for  the  trans- 
formation, namely, 

\a\k\=r^\aik\. 
This  condition  would  be  sufficient  if  the  coefficients  anc  and  the 
elements  of  the  determinant  r  were  constants.  In  our  case,  how- 
ever, other  conditions  must  be  satisfied,  namely,  the  conditions  of 
integrability  in  order  that  the  expressions  for  the  dx's  are  com- 
plete differentials.  This  is  the  way  in  which  Christoffel  introduces 
his  problem  to  the  reader. 

^  The  difficulty  lies  in  the  fact  that  the  integrability  conditions 
lead  at  once  to  a  great  number  of  partial  differential  equations  of 
an  apparently  highly  complex  character.  But  Christoffel  succeeds 
in  substituting  for  all  these  partial  differential  equations  a  purely 
algebraic  problem:  The  equivalence  of  two  finite  systems  of  alge- 
braic forms  in  the  sense  of  the  algebraic  theory  of  invariants.  If 
this  equivalence  is  satisfied,  —  which  is  merely  a  question  of  algebra, 

—  no  further  discussion  of  the  integrability  conditions  is  required; 
they  are  all  taken  care  of  by  the  equivalence  of  the  two  systems. 

For  the  following  it  will  be  necessary  to  sketch  briefly  the  char- 
acter of  these  forms. 

The  first  is  the  quadratic  form  A  itself.  The  next  form  is  a  quad- 
rilinear  covariant  G^  in  four  sets  of  differentials  dx^,  dx^,  dx^,  dx^, 
the  coefficients  of  which  are  precisely  the  quantities  {i  k  r  s  )  —  the 
"Christoffel  quadruple  index  symbols"  or  the  "Riemann  symbols" 

—  which  occur  in  the  expression  for  the  Riemann  curvature: 

G^=I(ikrs)  d'x^d'^Xj^d^x^d^Xg. 

It  is  highly  interesting  to  observe  how  the  quantities  {  i  k  r  s  ) 
have  entered  into  the  theory  from  two  so  apparently  different  stand- 
points. Christoffel  found  these  expressions  quite  independently. 
Though  Riemann 's  paper  was  written  in  1861,  that  is,  before  Chris- 
toffel's  article  which  appeared  in  1870,  it  w^as  only  published  in  1876, 
ten  years  after  Riemann 's  death,  by  Weber-Dedekind. 

For  the  deduction  of  the  following  forms  G^,  G^,  —  .  .  .  —  these 
forms  are  covariants  linear  in  resp.  5,6,  .  .  .  sets  of  differentials  — 
Christoffel  uses  a  certain  reduction  process.  The  coefficients  (Aikr  s) 
for  instance  of  G^  are  obtained  from  (i  k  r  s)  first  by  differentiating 
(i  k  r  s)  with  respect  to  x^  and  then  by  the  addition  of  a  sum  of  5n 
terms  which  are  linear  in  the  different  symbols  (i  k  r  s  )  with  co- 
efficients depending  on  the  so-called  Christoffel  triple  index  sym- 
bols of  the  second  kind  —  expressions  involving  the  quantities 
aik  and  their  first  derivatives. 


PROBLEMS  OF  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS    527 

Continuing  in  this  way  Christoffel  obtains  a  well-defined  set  of 
CO  variants  0^,0^,.  .  .  ,  and  this  is  his  final  result:  the  necessary 
and  sufficient  condition  for  the  equivalence  of  the  two  differential 
quadratics  is  the  algebraic  equivalence  —  in  the  sense  of  the  alge- 
braic theory  of  invariants —  of  the  forms  ^,  (t^,  (tj,  .  .  .  G^,andA'', 
G'^,  G\   .   .   .  G'^,  where  /x  is  a  certain  finite  number. 

In  several  papers  covering  the  period  from  about  1884  up  to  the 
present  time  Ricci  has  worked  out  in  a  systematical  way  the  funda- 
mental principles  of  Christoffel's  investigation,  and  has  applied  his 
theory  to  many  problems  in  analysis,  geometry,  mechanics,  and 
mathematical  physics.  He  recognized  in  particular  the  importance 
of  Christoffel's  deduction  of  the  co variants  G^j^^  from  G,^.  He  found 
that  this  process  of  deduction  can  be  applied  with  a  proper  modifi- 
cation to  any  functions  of  the  x's  and  the  a^/t's  and  that  whenever 
invariantive  relations  with  respect  to  the  fundamental  differential 
quadratic  A  come  into  question,  this  process  is  always  of  vital  im- 
portance. He  calls  this  process  covariantive  differentiation  with 
respect  to  the  fundamental  quadratic  A.  On  the  systematical  use 
of  this  covariantive  differentiation  Ricci  based  a  calculus  which  he 
called  Calcolo  differenziale  assoluto. 

A  collection  of  all  his  various  investigations  is  given  in  two  places : 

(1)  In  a  paper  published,  together  with  Levi-Civitta  in  the  Math, 
Annalen,  vol.  liv. 

(2)  In  his  Lezioni  sulla  teoria  delle  superficie,  Verona,  Padua,  1898. 
In  the  introduction  of  these  autographed  lectures  he  presents  a 

complete  exposition  of  his  absolute  differential  calculus.  Charac- 
teristic is  the  way  in  which  he  treats  in  his  Lezioni  the  differential 
geometry.    He  divides  it  into  two  parts: 

(1)  Properties  of  surfaces  depending  on  the  one  differential  quad- 
ratic ds^. 

(2)  Properties  of  surfaces  depending  on  the  two  quadratics 

ds^ 
ds^  and — . 

P 

We  are  here  chiefly  interested  in  his  applications  to  the  theory  of 

differential  invariants.    This  is  the  result  in  his  language:  In  order 

to  obtain  all  invariants  proper  and  differential  parameters  of  order  /i, 

it  is  sufficient  to  determine  the  algebraic  invariants  of  the  system 

of  the  following  forms: 

(1)  The  fundamental  differential  quantic  A. 

(2)  The  covariantive  derivatives  of  the  arbitrary  functions 

U,  V,  ...  up  to  the  order  /<. 

(3)  (for  fi>l)  the  quadrilinear  covariant  G^  and  its  covariantive 
derivatives  up  to  the  order  «  — 2. 

Another  treatment  of  the  invariant  theory  of  differential  quan- 


528  ALGEBRA   AND   ANALYSIS 

tics  was  given  by  myself.  I  applied  a  symbolic  method  to  the  theory 
which  consists  chiefly  in  identifying  the  fundamental  quadratic 

Ittikdxidxk 
with  the  square  of  a  linear  expression 

by  setting  jijk=<^ik-  This  is  strictly  analogous  to  the  introduction  of 
symbols  in  the  algebraic  theory.  The  difference,  of  course,  comes 
in  at  once  when  we  have  to  consider  also  the  derivatives  of  a^^. 

A  systematic  development  leads  to  expressions  and  formulas 
which  with  respect  to  simplicity  and  shortness  are  as  superior  to 
the  formulas  of  the  ordinary  notation  as  the  formulas  of  the  so- 
called  symbolic  notation  in  the  algebraic  theory  are  superior  to  the 
non-symbolic  expressions. 

As  examples  I  give  the  most  important  invariant  expressions 
for  the  case  n=2. 

Let  us  introduce  the  abbreviation 

(Pi  Q2  -P2  Qi  )  -(PQ),  where  Pk=^  ^tc; 


vaiia22  — a  12  oxk 

let  further  f,  (f,  (l>  .  .  .  be  symbols  of  A,  so  that 

and  let  C/,  y  ...  be  arbitrary  functions  oi  x^,  x^. 
Then  we  have 

Quy^A.  u, 

{jU){jV)=f{UV), 

{Km)  =^.u, 

(^^)   {(f'P)  (/^))    =2K  (Gaussian  curvature), 
Q(p)  (<pU)  {(fU)U)  :  (Ji  U)^  =Geodesic  curvature  of  curve  U  =  const. 
To  give  also  some  examples  of  simultaneous  invariant  expressions 
let  /,  ^,  .  .  .  be  as  before  symbols  of 

Edv?+2Fdudv+Gdv'' 
and  F,  0  .  .  .  symbols  of 

Ldu^+2Mdudv+Ndv\ 
Then: 

(F(Py=2K, 
(/P)^=mean  curvature. 
The  differential  equations 

of  asymptotic  curves  U  =  c  are  (FUy=0, 
of  conjugate  curves  U=c,  V=c:    (FU)(FV)=0, 
of  lines  of  curvature  U  =  c:    (jF) (fU) (FU)  =  0. 
The  equation  (f(p)(a>F){(f(p)U)  =0  gives  the  two  Cadazzi  formulas 
by  setting  the  coefficients  of  Ui  and  U2  separately  equal  to  zero. 

In  these  examples  the  invariant  expressions  always  appear  as 
products  of  factors  of  the  type  (PR).  The  general  theorem  holds 
that  any  product  of  factors  of  this  type  represents  always  an  in- 


PROBLEMS  OF  ALGEBRA  AND  ANALYSIS    529 

variant  expression  provided  that  the  symbols/,  ip,  .  .  .  ,  F,  0,  .  .  . 
occur  in  such  a  connection  as  to  permit  actual  meaning. 

The  symbolic  representation  of  invariant  expressions  suggested 
by  the  case  n=2  can  with6ut  essential  difficulty  be  extended  to  the 
general  case  of  n  variables.  In  this  treatment  of  the  subject  all  the 
essential  quantities  entering  into  the  theory  present  themselves  quite 
naturally;  they  lie,  so.  to  say,  on  the  surface;  so,  for  instance,  all  the 
Christoffel  symbols  of  the  different  kinds  including  the  Riemann 
symbols  and  in  particular  also  the  process  of  covariantive  differ- 
entiation. 

The  results  of  my  investigation  are  chiefly  laid  down  in  the  paper 
"A  symbolic  treatment  of  the  theory  of  invariants  of  quadratic 
differential  quantics  of  n  variables,"  Transactions  of  the  American 
Mathematical  Society,  vol.  iv. 

A  third  method  of  investigation  of  our  theory  of  invariants  is 
based  on  Lie's  theory  of  continuous  groups.  The  general  point 
transformation  by  which  A  is  transformed  into  A'  defines  a  so- 
called  "  infinite  "  continuous  group.  In  order  to  obtain  the  invari- 
ants of  A,  this  group  must  first  be  "extended"  in  Lie's  sense  to 
include  the  coefficients  aik  of  A  and  also  the  arbitrary  functions 
involved  in  the  differential  parameters. 

Lie  himself  developed  a  short  outline  of  the  determination  of 
invariants  in  the  second  volume  of  the  Mathematische  Annalen  for 
the  case  n=2,  and  indicated  in  particular  how  the  Gaussian  curv- 
ature and  the  parameter  Ji(p  could  be  found.  The  general  plan  of 
investigation  was  taken  up  in  the  sixteenth  volume  of  the  Acta 
Mathematica  by  Zorowski,  who  studied  the  case  n  =  2  in  detail,  adding 
the  complete  computation  of  the  Gaussian  curvature  and  the  most 
important  differential  parameters. 

An  extension  of  Lie's  methods  to  the  general  case  of  n  variables 
as  far  as  the  actual  determination  of  invariants  is  concerned  has, 
so  far  as  I  know,  not  yet  been  made;  only  the  problem  of  deter- 
mining the  number  of  functionally  independent  invariants  of  a  given 
order  has  been  taken  up.  It  seems  that  Lie's  method  is  especially 
well  adapted  to  this  particular  problem.  In  a  paper  in  the  Atti  del 
Reale  Instituto  Veneto  (1897),  Levi-Civitta  found  a  lower  limit  for  the 
number  of  invariants  of  a  given  order.  The  actual  number  was 
determined  by  Haskins  in  the  Transactions  of  the  American  Mathe- 
matical Society,  vol,  iii,  for  the  case  of  invariants  proper  (including 
also  simultaneous  invariants)  and  in  vol.  v,  of  differential  parameters. 

I  am  at  the  end  of  my  paper.  I  have  attempted  to  show,  in  a 
compendious  way,  what  has  been  done  in  this  attractive  field  of 
reseai'ch  which  is  so  closely  connected  with  various  interesting  parts 


530  ALGEBRA  AND   ANALYSIS 

of  pure  and  applied  mathematics.  The  number  of  problems  that  re- 
main to  be  solved  are  numerous.  Excepting  the  lowest  cases  as  to 
the  number  of  variables  and  the  order  of  the  invariants,  not  much 
more  than  the  mere  existence  of  the  invariants  is  known,  so  that 
we  have  hardly  the  right  to  speak  of  a  theory  of  these  invariants. 

When  it  comes  to  the  question  which  of  the  different  methods 
will  be  best  adapted  to  a  further  systematical  study  of  the  subject, 
it  seems  probable  that  a  combination  of  two  or  more  of  them  will 
be  the  most  promising  one.  But  here,  as  always,  it  is  the  man,  not 
the  method,  that  solves  the  problem, 


SHORT  PAPERS 

The  Section  of  Algebra  and  Analysis  attracted  wide  interest  and  caused  many 
supplementary  papers  on  various  topics  to  be  submitted.  It  is  impossible  to  give 
a  resume  of  these,  as  their  analytical  nature  demands  that  they  be  printed  in  full 
or  not  at  all. 

The  first  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  G.  A.  Miller,  of  Leland  Stanford  Jr. 
University,  on  the  "  Bearing  of  Several  Recent  Theorems  on  Group  Theory." 

The  second  paper  was  read  by  Professor  James  Birney  Shaw,  of  MiUiken 
University,  on  "  Linear  Associative  Algebra." 

The  third  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  M.  W.  Haskell,  of  the  University 
of  CaUfornia,  on  "The  Reduction  of  any  Collineation  to  a  Product  of  Perspect- 
ive CoUineations." 

The  fourth  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  M.  B.  Porter,  of  the  University 
of  Texas,  "  On  Functions  defined  by  an  Infinite  Series  of  Analytic  Functions 
of  a  Complex  Variable." 

The  fifth  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  Edward  V.  Huntington,  of  Harvard 
University,  on  "A  Set  of  Postulates  for  Real  Algebra  comprising  Postulates  for 
a  One  Dimensional  Continuum  and  for  the  Theory  of  Groups." 

The  sixth  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  J.  I.  Hutchinson,  of  Cornell  Uni- 
versity, on  "  Uniformizing  of  Algebraic  Functions." 

The  seventh  paper  was  read  by  Professor  E.  R.  Hedrick,  of  the  University  of 
Missouri,  on  "  Generalization  of  the  Analytic  Functions  of  a  Complex  Variable." 


SECTION    B  — GEOMETRY 


SECTION  B  — GEOMETRY 


{Hall  9,  September  24,  10  a.  m.) 

Chairman:  Professor  M.  W.  Haskell,  University  of  California. 
Speakers:  M.  Jean  Gaston  Darboux,  Perpetual  Secretary  of  the  Academy  of 
Sciences,  Paris. 
Dr.  Edward  Kasner,  Columbia  University. 
Secretary:  Professor  Thomas  J.  Holgate,  Northwestern  University. 


A     STUDY     OF     THE     DEVELOPMENT    OF     GEOMETRIC 

METHODS 

BY   M.    JEAN    GASTON   DAEBOUX 

{Translated  from  the  French  by  Professor  George  Bruce  Hoisted,  Kenyon  College) 

[Jean  Gaston  Darboux,  Perpetual  Secretary  Academy  of  Sciences,  Paris;  Doyen 
Honorary,  Professor  of  Higher  Geometry  of  the  Faculty  of  Sciences,  Paris. 
b.  August  13,  1842,  Nimes,  France.  Dr.Sc,  LL.D.,  University  of  Cambridge, 
University  of  Christiania,  University  of  Heidelberg,  et  al.  Professor  of 
Special  Mathematics,  Lycee  Louis  le  Grand,  1867-73;  Master  of  Confer- 
ences in  Superior  Normal  Schools,  Paris,  1873-81;  Professor  Suppliant  of 
Rational  Mechanics  and  Higher  Geometry,  The  Sorbonne,  1873-81;  since 
1881,  Professor  Titulaire  of  the  Faculty  of  Sciences,  and  Doyen  of  the  Fac- 
ulty of  Sciences  since  1889;  also  Professor  in  Higher  Normal  School  for 
Schools  of  Science  ;  Member  of  Bureau  des  Longitudes;  President  of  the 
First  General  Assembly  of  the  International  Association  of  Academies;  and 
Honorary  Vice-President  for  France  of  the  Congress  of  Arts  and  Science; 
Member  of  Institute  of  France,  Royal  Society  of  London;  Academies  of 
Berlin,  St.  Petersburg,  Rome,  Amsterdam,  Munich,  Stockholm;  American 
Philosophical  Society,  et  al.  Author  of  many  publications  and  addresses 
on  Mathematics,  and  editor  of  the  Bulletin  of  Science  of  Mathematics.] 


To  appreciate  the  progress  geometry  has  made  during  the  cen- 
tury just  ended,  it  is  of  advantage  to  cast  a  rapid  glance  over  the 
state  of  mathematical  science  at  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth 
century. 

We  know  that,  in  the  last  period  of  his  life,  Lagrange,  fatigued  by 
the  researches  in  analysis  and  mechanics,  which  assured  him,  however, 
an  immortal  glory,  neglected  mathematics  for  chemistry  (which, 
according  to  him,  was  easy  as  algebra),  for  physics,  for  philosophic 
speculations. 

This  mood  of  Lagraiige  we  almost  always  find  at  certain  moments 
of  the  life  of  the  greatest  savants.  The  new  ideas  which  came  to 
them  in  the  fecund  period  of  youth  and  which  they  introduced  into 
the  common  domain  have  given  them  all  they  could  have  expected; 
they  have  fulfilled  their  task  and  feel  the  need  of  turning  their 


536  GEOMETRY 

mental  activity  towards  wholly  new  subjects.  This  need,  as  we 
recognize,  manifested  itself  with  particular  force  at  the  epoch  of  La- 
grange. At  this  moment,  in  fact,  the  programme  of  researches  opened 
to  geometers  by  the  discovery  of  the  infinitesimal  calculus  appeared 
very  nearly  finished  up.  Some  differential  equations  more  or  less 
complicated  to  integrate,  some  chapters  to  add  to  the  integral 
calculus,  and  one  seemed  about  to  touch  the  very  outmost  bounds 
of  science. 

Laplace  had  achieved  the  explanation  of  the  system  of  the  world 
and  laid  the  foundations  of  molecular  physics.  New  ways  opened 
before  the  experimental  sciences  and  prepared  the  astonishing 
development  they  received  in  the  course  of  the  century  just  ended. 
Ampere,  Poisson,  Fourier,  and  Cauchy  himself,  the  creator  of  the 
theory  of  imaginaries,  were  occupied  above  all  in  studying  the  appli- 
cation of  the  analytic  methods  to  molecular  physics,  and  seemed  to 
believe  that  outside  this  new  domain,  which  they  hastened  to  cover, 
the  outlines  of  theory  and  science  were  finally  fixed. 

Modern  geometry,  a  glory  we  must  claim  for  it,  came,  after  the 
end  of  the  eighteenth  century,  to  contribute  in  large  measure  to  the 
renewing  of  all  mathematical  science,  by  offering  to  research  a  way 
new  and  fertile,  and  above  all  in  showing  us,  by  brilliant  successes, 
that  general  methods  are  not  everything  in  science,  and  that  even 
in  thfe  simplest  subject  there  is  much  for  an  ingenious  and  inventive 
mind  to  do. 

The  beautiful  geometric  demonstrations  of  Huygens,  of  Newton, 
and  of  Clairaut  were  forgotten  or  neglected.  The  fine  ideas  introduced 
by  Desargues  and  Pascal  had  remained  without  development  and 
appeared  to  have  fallen  on  sterile  ground. 

Carnot,  by  his  Essai  sur  les  transversales  and  his  Geometrie  de 
position,  above  all  Monge,  by  the  creation  of  descriptive  geometry 
and  by  his  beautiful  theories  on  the  generation  of  surfaces,  came  .to 
renew  a  chain  which  seemed  broken.  Thanks  to  them,  the  conceptions 
of  the  inventors  of  analytic  geometr}',  Descartes  and  Fermat,  retook 
alongside  the  infinitesimal  calculus  of  Leibnitz  and  Newton  the  place 
they  had  lost,  yet  should  never  have  ceased  to  occupy.  With  his 
geometry,  said  Lagrange,  speaking  of  Monge,  this  demon  of  a  man 
will  make  himself  immortal. 

And,  in  fact,  not  only  has  descriptive  geometry  made  it  possible 
to  coordinate  and  perfect  the  procedures  employed  in  all  the  arts 
where  precision  of  form  is  a  condition  of  success  and  of  excellence  for 
the  work  and  its  products;  but  it  appeared  as  the  graphic  translation 
of  a  geometry,  general  and  purely  rational,  of  which  numerous  and 
important  researches  have  demonstrated  the  happy  fertility. 

Moreover,  beside  the  Geometrie  descriptive  we  must  not  forget 
to  place  that  other  masterpiece,  the  Application  de  Vanalyse  a  la 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS   537 

geometrie  ;  nor  should  we  forget  that  to  Monge  are  due  the  notion 
of  hnes  of  curvature  and  the  elegant  integration  of  the  differential 
equation  of  these  lines  for  the  case  of  the  ellipsoid,  which,  it  is  said, 
Lagrange  envied  him.  To  be  stressed  is  this  character  of  unity  of  the 
work  of  Monge. 

The  renewer  of  modern  geometry  has  shown  us  from  the  beginning, 
what  his  successors  have  perhaps  forgotten,  that  the  alliance  of 
geometry  and  analysis  is  useful  and  fruitful,  that  this  alliance  is 
perhaps  for  each  a  condition  of  success. 

II 

In  the  school  of  Monge  were  formed  many  geometers:  Hachette, 
Brianchon,  Chappuis,  Binet,  Lancret,  Dupin,  Malus,  Gaultier  de 
Tours,  Poncelet,  Chasles,  et  al.  Among  these  Poncelet  takes  first 
rank.  Neglecting,  in  the  works  of  Monge,  everything  pertaining  to 
the  analysis  of  Descartes  or  concerning  infinitesimal  geometry,  he 
devoted  himself  exclusively  to  developing  the  germs  contained  in 
the  purely  geometric  researches  of  his  illustrious  predecessor. 

Made  prisoner  by  the  Russians  in  1813  at  the  passage  of  the  Dnieper 
and  incarcerated  at  Saratoff,  Poncelet  employed  the  leisure  captivity 
left  him  in  the  demonstration  of  the  principles  which  he  has  developed 
in  the  Traite  des  proprietes  projectives  des  figures,  issued  in  1822,. 
and  in  the  great  memoirs  on  reciprocal  polars  and  on  harmonic 
means,  which  go  back  nearly  to  the  same  epoch.  So  we  may  say  the 
modern  geometry  was  born  at  Saratoff. 

Renewing  the  chain  broken  since  Pascal  and  Desargues,  Poncelet 
introduced  at  the  same  time  homology  and  reciprocal  polars,  putting 
thus  in  evidence,  from  the  beginning,  the  fruitful  ideas  on  which  the 
science  has  evolved  during  fifty  years. 

Presented  in  opposition  to  analytic  geometry,  the  methods  of  Ponce- 
let were  not  favorably  received  by  the  French  analysts.  But  such 
were  their  importance  and  their  novelty,  that  without  delay  they 
aroused,  from  divers  sides,  the  most  profound  researches. 

Poncelet  had  been  alone  in  discovering  the  principles;  on  the 
contrary,  many  geometers  appeared  almost  simultaneously  to  study 
them  on  all  sides  and  to  deduce  from  them  the  essential  results  which 
they  implicitly  contained. 

At  this  epoch,  Gergonne  was  brilliantly  editing  a  periodical  which 
has  to-day  for  the  history  of  geometry  an  inestimable  value.  The 
Afinales  de  Mathematiques,  published  at  Nimes  from  1810  to  1831^ 
was  during  more  than  fifteen  years  the  only  journal  in  the  entire 
world  devoted  exclusively  to  mathematical  researches. 

Gergonne,  who,  in  many  regards,  was  a  model  editor  for  a  scienti- 
fic journal,  had  the  defects  of  his  qualities;   he  collaborated,  often 


538  GEOMETRY 

against  their  will,  with  the  authors  of  the  memoirs  sent  him,  rewrote 
them,  and  sometimes  made  them  say  more  or  less  than  they  would 
have  wished.  Be  that  as  it  may,  he  was  greatly  struck  by  the  origin- 
ality and  range  of  Poncelet's  discoveries. 

In  geometry  some  simple  methods  of  transformation  of  figures 
were  already  known;  homology  even  had  been  employed  in  the  plane, 
but  without  extending  it  to  space,  as  did  Poncelet,  and  especially 
without  recognizing  its  power  and  fruitfulness.  Moreover,  all  these 
transformations  were  punctual ;  that  is  to  say,  they  made  correspond 
a  point  to  a  point. 

In  introducing  polar  reciprocals,  Poncelet  was  in  the  highest 
degree  creative,  because  he  gave  the  first  example  of  a  transformation 
in  which  to  a  point  corresponded  something  other  than  a  point. 

Every  method  of  transformation  enables  us  to  multiply  the  num- 
ber of  theorems,  but  that  of  polar  reciprocals  had  the  advantage  of 
making  correspond  to  a  proposition  another  proposition  of  wholly 
different  aspect.  This  was  a  fact  essentially  new.  To  put  it  in  evi- 
dence, Gergonne  invented  the  system,  which  since  has  had  so  much 
success,  of  memoirs  printed  in  double  columns  with  correlative 
propositions  in  juxtaposition;  and  he  had  the  idea  of  substituting 
for  Poncelet's  demonstrations,  which  required  an  intermediary 
curve  or  surface  of  the  second  degree,  the  famous  "principle  of 
duality,"  of  which  the  signification,  a  little  vague  at  first,  was  suffi- 
ciently cleared  up  by  the  discussions  which  took  place  on  this  subject 
between  Gergonne,  Poncelet,  and  Pluecker. 

Bobillier,  Chasles,  Steiner,  Lame,  Sturm,  and  many  others  whose 
names  escape  me,  were,  at  the  same  time  as  Pluecker  and  Poncelet, 
assiduous  collaborators  of  the  Annales  de  Mathematiques.  Gergonne, 
having  become  rector  of  the  Academy  of  Montpellier,  was  forced  to 
suspend  in  1831  the  publication  of  his  journal.  But  the  success  it  had 
obtained,  the  taste  for  research  it  had  contributed  to  develop,  had 
commenced  to  bear  their  fruit.  Quetelet  had  established  in  Belgium 
the  Correspondance  mathematique  et  physique.  Crelle,  from  1826, 
brought  out  at  Berlin  the  first  sheets  of  his  celebrated  journal,  where 
he  published  the  memoirs  of  Abel,  of  Jacobi,  of  Steiner. 

A  great  number  of  separate  works  began  also  to  appear,  wherein 
the  principles  of  modern  geometry  were  powerfully  expounded  and 
developed. 

First  came  in  1827  the  Barycentrische  Calcul  of  Moebius,  a  work 
truly  original,  remarkable  for  the  profundity  of  its  conceptions,  the 
elegance  and  the  rigor  of  its  exposition;  then  in  1828  the  Analytisch- 
geometrische  Entioickelungen  of  Pluecker,  of  which  the  second  part 
appeared  in  1831,  and  which  was  soon  followed  by  the  System  der 
analytischen  Geometrie  of  the  same  author,  published  at  Berlin  in 
1835. 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS   539 

In  1832  Steiner  brought  out  at  Berlin  his  great  work:  Systemat- 
ische  Entmckelung  der  Ahhaengigkeit  der  geometrischen  Gestalten  von 
einander,  and,  the  following  year,  Die  geometrischen  Konstruktionen 
ausgefuehrt  mittels  der  geraden  Linie  und  eines  festen  Kreises,  where 
was  confirmed  by  the  most  elegant  examples  a  proposition  of  Pon- 
celet's  relative  to  the  employment  of  a  single  circle  for  the  geometric 
constructions. 

Finally,  in  1830,  Chasles  sent  to  the  Academy  of  Brussels,  which 
happily  inspired  had  offered  a  prize  for  a  study  of  the  principles  of 
modern  geometry,  his  celebrated  Apercu  historique  sur  Vorigine  et 
le  developpement  des  methodes  en  geometrie,  followed  by  Memoirs 
sur  deux  principes  generaux  de  la  science :  la  dualite  et  Vhomographie, 
which  was  published  only  in  1837. 

Time  would  fail  us  to  give  a  worthy  appreciation  of  these  beautiful 
works  and  to  apportion  the  share  of  each.  Moreover,  to  what  would 
such  a  study  conduct  us,  but  to  a  new  verification  of  the  general  laws 
of  the  development  of  science  ?  When  the  times  are  ripe,  when  the 
fundamental  principles  have  been  recognized  and  enunciated,  nothing 
stops  the  march  of  ideas  ;  the  same  discoveries,  or  discoveries  almost 
equivalent,  appear  at  nearly  the  same  instant,  and  in  places  the  most 
diverse.  Without  undertaking  a  discussion  of  this  sort,  which,  besides, 
might  appear  useless  or  become  irritating,  it  is,  however,  of  import- 
ance to  bring  out  a  fundamental  difference  between  the  tendencies 
of  the  great  geometers,  who,  about  1830,  gave  to  geometry  a  scope 
before  unknown. 

Ill 

Some,  like  Chasles  and  Steiner,  who  consecrated  their  entire  lives 
to  research  in  pure  geometry,  opposed  what  they  called  synthesis  to 
analysis,  and,  adopting  in  the  ensemble  if  not  in  detail  the  tendencies 
of  Poncelet,  proposed  to  constitute  an  independent  doctrine,  rival  of 
Descartes's  analysis. 

Poncelet  could  not  content  himself  with  the  insufficient  resources 
furnished  by  the  method  of  projections;  to  attain  imaginaries  he 
created  that  famous  principle  of  continuity  which  gave  birth  to  such 
long  discussions  between  him  and  Cauchy. 

Suitably  enunciated,  this  principle  is  excellent  and  can  render 
great  service.  Poncelet  was  wrong  in  refusing  to  present  it  as  a  simple 
consequence  of  analysis;  and  Cauchy,  on  the  other  hand,  was  not 
willing  to  recognize  that  his  own  objections,  applicable  without 
doubt  to  certain  transcendent  figures,  were  without  force  in  the 
applications  made  by  the  author  of  the  Traits  des  proprietes  pro- 
jectives. 

Whatever  be  the  opinion  of  such  a  discussion,  it  showed  at  least 
in  the  clearest  manner  that  the  geometric  system  of  Poncelet  rested 


540  GEOMETRY 

on  an  analytic  foundation,  and  besides  we  know,  by  the  untoward 
publication  of  the  manuscripts  of  Saratoff,  that  by  the  aid  of 
Descartes 's  analysis  were  established  the  principles  which  serve  as 
foundation  for  the  Traite  des  proprietes  projectives. 

Younger  than  Poncelet,  who  besides  abandoned  geometry  for 
mechanics  where  his  works  had  a  preponderant  influence,  Chasles, 
for  whom  was  created  in  1847  a  chair  of  Geometrie  superieure  in  the 
Faculty  of  Science  of  Paris,  endeavored  to  constitute  a  geometric 
doctrine  entirely  independent  and  autonomous.  He  has  expounded 
it  in  two  works  of  high  importance,  the  Traite  de  geometrie  supe- 
rieure, which  dates  from  1852,  and  the  Traite  des  sections  coniques, 
unhappily  unfinished  and  of  which  the  first  part  alone  appeared  in 
1865. 

In  the  preface  of  the  first  of  these  works  he  indicates  very  clearly 
the  three  fundamental  points  which  permit  the  new  doctrine  to  share 
the  advantages  of  analysis  and  which  to  him  appear  to  mark  an 
advance  in  the  cultivation  of  the  science.  These  are:  (1)  The  intro- 
duction of  the  principle  of  signs,  which  simplifies  at  once  the  enuncia- 
tions and  the  demonstrations,  and  gives  to  Carnot's  analysis  of  trans- 
versals all  the  scope  of  which  it  is  susceptible;  (2)  the  introduction  of 
imaginaries,  which  supplies  the  place  of  the  principle  of  continuity 
and  furnishes  demonstrations  as  general  as  those  of  analytic  geo- 
metry; (3)  the  simultaneous  demonstration  of  propositions  which  are, 
correlative,  that  is  to  say,  which  correspond  in  virtue  of  the  principle 
of  duality. 

Chasles  studies  indeed  in  his  work  homography  and  correlation; 
but  he  avoids  systematically  in  his  exposition  the  employment  of 
transformations  of  figures,  which,  he  thinks,  cannot  take  the  place  of 
direct  demonstrations  since  they  mask  the  origin  and  the  true  nature 
of  the  properties  obtained  by  their  means. 

There  is  truth  in  this  judgment,  but  the  advance  itself  of  the  science 
permits  us  to  declare  it  too  severe.  If  it  happens  often  that,  em- 
ployed without  discernment,  transformations  multiply  uselessly  the 
number  of  theorems,  it  must  be  recognized  that  they  often  aid  us  to 
better  understand  the  nature  of  the  propositions  even  to  which  they 
have  been  applied.  Is  it  not  the  employment  of  Poncelet's  projection 
which  has  led  to  the  so  fruitful  distinction  between  projective  proper- 
ties and  metric  properties,  which  has  taught  us  also  the  high  import- 
ance of  that  cross-ratio  whose  essential  property  is  found  already 
in  Pappus,  and  of  which  the  fundamental  role  has  begun  to  appear 
after  fifteen  centuries  only  in  the  researches  of  modern  geometry? 

The  introduction  of  the  principle  of  signs  was  not  so  new  as  Chasles 
supposed  at  the  time  he  wrote  his  Traite  de  Geometrie  superieure. 

Moebius,  in  his  Barycentrische  Calcul,  had  already  given  issue  to 
a  desideratum  of  Carnot,  and  employed  the  signs  in  a  way  the  largest 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   GEOMETRIC   METHODS        541 

and  most  precise,  defining  for  the  first  time  the  sign  of  a  segment 
and  even  that  of  an  area. 

Later  he  succeeded  in  extending  the  use  of  signs  to  lengths  not 
laid  off  on  the  same  straight  line  and  to  angles  not  formed  about  the 
same  point. 

Besides  Grassmann,  whose  mind  has  so  much  analogy  to  that  of 
Moebius,  had  necessarily  employed  the  principle  of  signs  in  the  defini- 
tions which  serve  as  basis  for  his  methods,  so  original,  of  studying 
the  properties  of  space. 

The  second  characteristic  which  Chasles  assigns  to  his  system  of 
geometry  is  the  employment  of  imaginaries.  Here,  his  method  was 
really  new,  and  he  illustrates  it  by  examples  of  high  interest.  One  will 
always  admire  the  beautiful  theories  he  has  left  us  on  homofocal 
surfaces  of  the  second  degree,  where  all  the  known  properties  and 
others  new,  as  varied  as  elegant,  flow  from  the  general  principle  that 
they  are  inscribed  in  the  same  developable  circumscribed  to  the 
circle  at  infinity. 

But  Chasles  introduced  imaginaries  only  by  their  symmetric  func- 
tions, and  consequently  would  not  have  been  able  to  define  the  cross- 
ratio  of  four  elements  when  these  ceased  to  be  real  in  whole  or  in 
part.  If  Chasles  had  been  able  to  establish  the  notion  of  the  cross- 
ratio  of  imaginary  elements,  a  formula  he  gives  in  the  Geometrie 
superieure  (p.  118  of  the  new  edition)  would  have  immediately 
furnished  him  that  beautiful  definition  of  angle  as  logarithm  of  a 
cross-ratio  which  enabled  Laguerre,  our  regretted  confrere,  to  give 
the  complete  solution,  sought  so  long,  of  the  problem  of  the  trans- 
formation of  relations  which  contain  at  the  same  time  angles  and 
segments  in  homography  and  correlation. 

Like  Chasles,  Steiner,  the  great  and  profound  geometer,  followed 
the  way  of  pure  geometry;  but  he  has  neglected  to  give  us  a  complete 
exposition  of  the  methods  upon  which  he  depended.  However,  they 
may  be  characterized  by  saying  that  they  rest  upon  the  introduction 
of  those  elementary  geometric  forms  which  Desargues  had  already 
considered,  on  the  development  he  was  able  to  give  to  Bobillier's 
theory  of  polars,  and  finally  on  the  construction  of  curves  and  sur- 
faces of  higher  degrees  by  the  aid  of  sheaves  or  nets  of  curves  of 
lower  orders.  In  default  of  recent  researches,  analysis  would  suffice 
to  show  that  the  field  thus  embraced  has  just  the  extent  of  that  into 
which  the  analysis  of  Descartes  introduces  us  without  effort. 

IV 

While  Chasles,  Steiner,  and,  later,  as  we  shall  see,  von  Staudt,  were 
intent  on  constituting  a  rival  doctrine  to  analysis  and  set  in  some 
sort  altar  against  altar,  Gergonne,  Bobillier,  Sturm,  and  above  all 
Pluecker,  perfected  the  geometry  of  Descartes  and  constituted  an 


542  GEOMETRY 

analytic  system  in  a  manner  adequate  to  the  discoveries  of  the 
geometers.  It  is  to  Bobillier  and  to  Pluecker  that  we  owe  the  method 
called  abridged  notation.  Bobillier  consecrated  to  it  some  pages  truly 
new  in  the  last  volumes  of  the  Annates  of  Gergonne. 

Pluecker  commenced  to  develop  it  in  his  first  work,  soon  followed 
by  a  series  of  works  where  are  established  in  a  fully  conscious  manner 
the  foundations  of  the  modern  analytic  geometry.  It  is  to  him  that 
we  owe  tangential  coordinates,  trilinear  coordinates,  employed  with 
homogeneous  equations,  and  finally  the  employment  of  canonical 
forms  whose  validity  was  recognized  by  the  method,  so  deceptive 
sometimes,  but  so  fruitful,  called  the  enumeration  of  constants. 

All  these  happy  acquisitions  infused  new  blood  into  Descartes's 
analysis  and  put  it  in  condition  to  give  their  full  signification  to  the 
conceptions  of  which  the  geometry  called  synthetic  had  been  unable 
to  make  itself  completely  mistress. 

Pluecker,  to  whom  it  is  without  doubt  just  to  adjoin  Bobillier, 
carried  off  by  a  premature  death,  should  be  regarded  as  the  veritable 
initiator  of  those  methods  of  modern  analysis  where  the  employment 
of  homogeneous  coordinates  permits  treating  simultaneously  and, 
so  to  say,  without  the  reader  perceiving  it,  together  with  one  figure 
all  those  deducible  from  it  by  homography  and  correlation. 


Parting  from  this  moment,  a  period  opens  brilliant  for  geometric 
researches  of  every  nature. 

The  analysts  interpret  all  their  results  and  are  occupied  in  trans- 
lating them  by  constructions. 

The  geometers  are  intent  on  discovering  in  every  question  some 
general  principle,  usually  undemonstrable  without  the  aid  of  ana- 
lysis, in  order  to  make  flow  from  it  without  effort  a  crowd  of  particu- 
lar consequences,  solidly  bound  to  one  another  and  to  the  principle 
whence  they  are  derived.  Otto  Hesse,  brilliant  disciple  of  Jacobi, 
develops  in  an  admirable  manner  that  method  of  homogeneous 
coordinates  to  which  Pluecker  perhaps  had  not  attached  its  full 
value.  Boole  discovers  in  the  polars  of  Bobillier  the  first  notion  of 
a  CO  variant ;  the  theory  of  forms  is  created  by  the  labors  of  Cayley , 
Sylvester,  Hermite,  Brioschi.  Later  Aronhold,  Clebsch  and  Gordan, 
and  other  geometers  still  living,  gave  to  it  its  final  notation,  estab- 
lished the  fundamental  theorem  relative  to  the  limitation  of  the 
number  of  covariant  forms  and  so  gave  it  all  its  amplitude. 

The  theory  of  surfaces  of  the  second  order,  built  up  principally 
by  the  school  of  Monge,  was  enriched  by  a  multitude  of  elegant 
properties,  established  principally  by  O.  Hesse,  who  found  later  in 
Paul  Serret  a  worthy  emulator  and  continuer. 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS    543 

The  properties  of  the  polars  of  algebraic  curves  are  developed  by 
Pluecker  and  above  all  by  Steiner.  The  study,  already  old,  of  curves 
of  the  third  order  is  rejuvenated  and  enriched  by  a  crowd  of  new 
elements.  Steiner,  the  first,  studies  by  pure  geometry  the  double 
tangents  of  curves  of  the  fourth  order,  and  Hesse,  after  him,  appUes 
the  methods  of  algebra  to  this  beautiful  question,  as  well  as  to  that 
of  points  of  inflection  of  curves  of  the  third  order. 

The  notion  of  class  introduced  by  Gergonne,  the  study  of  a  para- 
dox in  part  elucidated  by  Poncelet  and  relative  to  the  respective 
degrees  of  two  curves  reciprocal  polars  one  of  the  other,  give  birth 
to  the  researches  of  Pluecker  relative  to  the  singularities  called  ordi- 
nary of  algebraic  plane  curves.  The  celebrated  formulas  to  which 
Pluecker  is  thus  conducted  are  later  extended  by  Cayley  and  by 
other  geometers  to  algebraic  skew  curves,  by  Cayley  again  and  by 
Salmon  to  algebraic  surfaces. 

The  singularities  of  higher  order  are  in  their  turn  taken  up  by 
the  geometers;  contrary  to  an  opinion  then  very  widespread,  Hal- 
phen  demonstrates  that  each  of  these  singularities  cannot  be  con- 
sidered as  equivalent  to  a  certain  group  of  ordinary  singularities,  and 
his  researches  close  for  a  time  this  difficult  and  important  question. 

Analysis  and  geometry,  Steiner,  Cayley,  Salmon,  Cremona,  meet  in 
the  study  of  surfaces  of  the  third  order,  and,  in  conformity  with 
the  anticipations  of  Steiner,  this  theory  becomes  as  simple  and  as 
easy  as  that  of  surfaces  of  the  second  order. 

The  algebraic  ruled  surfaces,  so  important  for  applications,  are 
studied  by  Chasles,  by  Cayley,  of  whom  we  find  the  influence  and  the 
mark  in  all  mathematical  researches,  by  Cremona,  Salmon,  La  Gour- 
nerie;  so  they  will  be  later  by  Pluecker  in  a  work  to  which  we  must 
return. 

The  study  of  the  general  surface  of  the  fourth  order  would  seem 
to  be  still  too  difficult;  but  that  of  the  particular  surfaces  of  this  order 
with  multiple  points  or  multiple  lines  is  commenced,  by  Pluecker  for 
the  surface  of  waves,  by  Steiner,  Kummer,  Cayley,  Moutard,  Laguerre, 
Cremona,  and  many  other  investigators. 

As  for  the  theory  of  algebraic  skew  curves,  grown  rich  in  its  ele- 
mentary parts,  it  receives  finally,  by  the  labors  of  Halphen  and  of 
Noether,  whom  it  is  impossible  for  us  here  to  separate,  the  most 
notable  extensions. 

A  new  theory  with  a  great  future  is  bom  by  the  labors  of  Chasles, 
of  Clebsch,  and  of  Cremona;  it  concerns  the  study  of  all  the  algebraic 
curves  which  can  be  traced  on  a  determined  surface. 

Homography  and  correlation,  those  two  methods  of  transformation 
which  have  been  the  distant  origin  of  all  the  preceding  researches, 
receive  from  them  in  their  turn  an  unexpected  extension;  they  are 
not  the  only  methods  which  make  a  single  element  correspond  to  a 


544  GEOMETRY 

single  element,  as  might  have  shown  a  particular  transformation 
briefly  indicated  by  Poncelet  in  the  Traite  des  proprietes  projectives. 

Pluecker  defines  the  transformation  by  reciprocal  radii  vectores  or 
inversion,  of  which  Sir  W.  Thomson  and  Liouville  hasten  to  show  all 
the  importance,  as  well  for  mathematical  physics  as  for  geometry. 

A  contemporary  of  Moebius  and  Pluecker,  Magnus  believed  he  had 
found  the  most  general  transformation  which  makes  a  point  corre- 
spond to  a  point,  but  the  researches  of  Cremona  show  us  that  the 
transformation  of  Magnus  is  only  the  first  term  of  a  series  of  bira- 
tional  transformations  which  the  great  Italian  geometer  teaches  us  to 
determine  methodically,  at  least  for  the  figures  of  plane  geometry. 

The  Cremona  transformations  long  retained  a  great  interest, 
though  later  researches  have  shown  us  that  they  reduce  always  to 
a  series  of  successive  applications  of  the  transformation  of  Magnus. 

VI 

All  the  works  we  have  enumerated,  others  to  which  we  shall  return 
later,  find  their  origin  and,  in  some  sort,  their  first  motive  in  the  con- 
ceptions of  modern  geometry;  but  the  moment  has  come  to  indicate 
rapidly  another  source  of  great  advances  for  geometric  studies. 
Legendre's  theory  of  elliptic  functions,  too  much  neglected  by  the 
French  geometers,  is  developed  and  extended  by  Abel  and  Jacobi. 
With  these  great  geometers,  soon  followed  by  Riemann  and  Weier- 
strass,  the  theory  of  Abelian  functions  which,  later,  algebra  would 
try  to  follow  solely  with  its  own  resources,  brought  to  the  geometry 
of  curves  and  surfaces  a  contribution  whose  importance  will  continue 
to  grow. 

Already,  Jacobi  had  employed  the  analysis  of  elliptic  functions 
in  the  demonstration  of  Poncelet 's  celebrated  theorems  on  inscribed 
and  circumscribed  polygons,  inaugurating  thus  a  chapter  since  en- 
riched by  a  multitude  of  elegant  results;  he  had  obtained  also,  by 
methods  pertaining  to  geometry,  the  integration  of  Abelian  equa- 
tions. 

But  it  was  Clebsch  who  first  showed  in  a  long  series  of  works  all 
the  importance  of  the  notion  of  deficiency  (Geschlecht,  genre)  of  a 
curve,  due  to  Abel  and  Riemann,  in  developing  a  crowd  of  results 
and  elegant  solutions  that  the  employment  of  Abelian  integrals  would 
seem,  so  simple  was  it,  to  connect  with  their  veritable  point  of 
departure. 

The  study  of  points  of  inflection  of  curves  of  the  third  order,  that 
of  double  tangents  of  curves  of  the  fourth  order,  and,  in  general,  the 
theory  of  osculation  on  Avhich  the  ancients  and  the  moderns  had  so 
often  practiced,  were  connected  with  the  beautiful  problem  of  the 
division  of  elliptic  functions  and  Abelian  functions. 

In  one  of  his  memoirs,  Clebsch  had  studied  the  curves  which  are 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS    545 

rational  or  of  deficiency  zero;  this  led  him,  toward  the  end  of  his 
too  short  life,  to  envisage  what  may  be  called  also  rational  surfaces, 
those  which  can  be  simply  represented  by  a  plane.  This  was  a  vast 
field  for  research,  opened  already  for  the  elementary  cases  by  Chasles, 
and  in  which  Clebsch  was  followed  by  Cremona  and  many  other 
savants.  It  was  on  this  occasion  that  Cremona,  generalizing  his  re- 
searches on  plane  geometry,  made  known  not  indeed  the  totality  of 
birational  transformations  of  space,  but  certain  of  the  most  interest- 
ing among  these  transformations. 

The  extension  of  the  notion  of  deficiency  to  algebraic  surfaces  is 
already  commenced;  already  also  works  of  high  value  have  shown 
that  the  theory  of  integrals,  simple  or  multiple,  of  algebraic  differ- 
entials will  find,  in  the  study  of  surfaces  as  in  that  of  curves,  an  ample 
field  of  important  applications;  but  it  is  not  proper  for  the  reporter 
on  geometry  to  dilate  on  this  subject . 

VII 

While  thus  were  constituted  the  mixed  methods  whose  principal 
applications  we  have  just  indicated,  the  pure  geometers  were  not 
inactive.  Poinsot,  the  creator  of  the  theory  of  couples,  developed, 
bj"-  a  method  purely  geometric,  "that,  where  one  never  for  a  mo- 
ment loses  from  view  the  object  of  the  research,"  the  theory  of  the 
rotation  of  a  solid  body  that  the  researches  of  d'Alembert,  Euler,  and 
Lagrange  seemed  to  have  exhausted;  Chasles  made  a  precious  con- 
tribution to  kinematic  by  his  beautiful  theorems  on  the  displacement 
of  a  solid  body,  which  have  since  been  extended  by  other  elegant 
methods  to  the  case  where  the  motion  has  divers  degrees  of  freedom. 
He  made  known  those  beautiful  propositions  on  attraction  in  gen- 
eral, which  figure  without  disadvantage  beside  those  of  Green  and 
Gauss.  Chasles  and  Steiner  met  in  the  study  of  the  attraction  of 
ellipsoids  and  showed  thus  once  more  that  geometry  has  its  desig- 
nated place  in  the  highest  questions  of  the  integral  calculus. 

Steiner  did  not  disdain  at  the  same  time  to  occupy  himself  with 
the  elementary  parts  of  geometry.  His  researches  on  the  contacts  of 
circles  and  conies,  on  isoperimetric  problems,  on  parallel  surfaces,  on 
the  centre  of  gravity  of  curvature,  excited  the  admiration  of  all  by 
their  simplicity  and  their  depth. 

Chasles  introduced  his  principle  of  correspondence  between  two 
variable  objects  which  has  given  birth  to  so  many  applications;  but 
here  analysis  retook  its.  place  to  study  the  principle  in  its  essence, 
make  it  precise  and  generalize  it. 

It  was  the  same  concerning  the  famous  theory  of  characteristics 
and  the  numerous  researches  of  de  Jonquieres,  Chasles,  Cremona, 
and  still  others,  which  gave  the  foundations  of  a  new  branch  of  the 
science,  Enumerative  Geometry. 


546  GEOMETRY 

During  many  years,  the  celebrated  postulate  of  Chasles  was  ad- 
mitted without  any  objection:  a  crowd  of  geometers  believed  they 
had  established  it  in  a  manner  irrefutable. 

But,  as  Zeuthen  then  said,  it  is  very  difficult  to  recognize  whether, 
in  demonstrations  of  this  sort,  there  does  not  exist  always  some  weak 
point  that  their  author  has  not  perceived;  and,  in  fact,  Halphen, 
after  fruitless  efforts,  crowned  finally  all  these  researches  by  clearly 
indicating  in  what  cases  the  postulate  of  Chasles  may  be  admitted 
and  in  what  cases  it  must  be  rejected. 

VIII 

Such  are  the  principal  works  which  restored  geometric  synthesis 
to  honor  and  assured  to  it,  in  the  course  of  the  last  century,  the  place 
belonging  to  it  in  mathematical  research.  Numerous  and  illustrious 
workers  took  part  in  this  great  geometric  movement,  but  we  must 
recognize  that  its  chiefs  and  leaders  were  Chasles  and  Steiner.  So 
brilliant  were  their  marvelous  discoveries  that  they  threw  into  the 
shade,  at  least  momentarily,  the  publications  of  other  modest  geo- 
meters, less  preoccupied  perhaps  in  finding  brilliant  applications, 
fitted  to  evoke  love  for  geometry  than  to  establish  this  science  itself 
on  an  absolutely  solid  foundation.  Their  works  have  received  per- 
haps a  recompense  more  tardy,  but  their  influence  grows  each  day; 
it  will  assuredly  increase  still  more.  To  pass  them  over  in  silence 
would  be  without  doubt  to  neglect  one  of  the  principal  factors  which 
will  enter  into  future  researches.  We  allude  at  this  moment  above 
all  to  von  Staudt.  His  geometric  works  were  published  in  two  books 
of  great  interest:  the  Geometrie  der  Lage,  issued  in  1847,  and  the 
Beitrage  zur  Geometrie  der  Lage,  published  in  1856,  that  is  to  say, 
four  years  after  the  Geometrie  swperieure.  Chasles,  as  we  have  seen, 
had  devoted  himself  to  constituting  a  body  of  doctrine  independent 
of  Descartes's  analysis  and  had  not  completely  succeeded.  We  have 
already  indicated  one  of  the  criticisms  that  can  be  made  upon  this 
system:  the  imaginary  elements  are  there  defined  only  by  their  sym- 
metric functions,  which  necessarily  exclude  them  from  a  multitude 
of  researches.  On  the  other  hand,  the  constant  employment  of  cross- 
ratio,  of  transversals,  and  of  involution,  which  requires  frequent 
analytic  transformations,  gives  to  the  Geometrie  swperieure  a  char- 
acter almost  exclusively  metric  which  removes  it  notably  from  the 
methods  of  Poncelet.  Returning  to  these  methods,  von  Staudt 
devoted  himself  to  constituting  a  geometry  freed  from  all  metric 
relation  and  resting  exclusively  on  relations  of  situation. 

This  is  the  spirit  in  which  was  conceived  his  first  work,  the  Geo- 
metrie der  Lage  of  1847.  The  author  there  takes  as  point  of  departure 
the  harmonic  properties  of  the  complete  quadrilateral  and  those 
of  homologic  triangles,  demonstrated  uniquely  by  considerations 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS    547 

of  geometry  of  three  dimensions,  analogous  to  those  of  which  the 
school  of  Monge  made  such  frequent  use. 

In  this  first  part  of  his  work,  von  Staudt  neglected  entirely  im- 
aginary elements.  It  is  only  in  the  Beitrage,  his  second  work,  that 
he  succeeds,  by  a  very  original  extension  of  the  method  of  Chasles, 
in  defining  geometrically  an  isolated  imaginary  element  and  dis- 
tinguishing it  from  its  conjugate. 

This  extension,  although  rigorous,  is  difficult  and  very  abstract. 
It  may  be  defined  in  substance  as  follows:  Two  conjugate  imaginary 
points  may  always  be  considered  as  the  double  points  of  an  involu- 
tion on  a  real  straight;  and  just  as  one  passes  from  an  imaginary  to 
its  conjugate  by  changing  i  into  — i,  so  one  may  distinguish  the  two 
imaginary  points  by  making  correspond  to  each  of  them  one  of  the 
two  different  senses  which  may  be  attributed  to  the  straight.  In  this 
there  is  something  a  little  artificial;  the  development  of  the  theory 
erected  on  such  foundations  is  necessarily  complicated.  By  methods 
purely  projective,  von  Staudt  establishes  a  calculus  of  cross-ratios  of 
the  most  general  imaginary  elements.  Like  all  geometry,  the  pro- 
jective geometry  employs  the  notion  of  order  and  order  engenders 
number;  we  are  not  astonished  therefore  that  von  Staudt  has  been 
able  to  constitute  his  calculus;  but  we  must  admire  the  ingenuity 
displayed  in  attaining  it.  In  spite  of  the  efforts  of  distinguished 
geometers  who  have  essayed  to  simplify  its  exposition,  we  fear  that 
this  part  of  the  geometry  of  von  Staudt,  like  the  geometry  otherwise 
so  interesting  of  the  profound  thinker  Grassmann,  cannot  prevail 
against  the  analytical  methods  which  have  won  to-day  favor  almost 
universal.  Life  is  short;  geometers  know  and  also  practice  the 
principle  of  least  action.  Despite  these  fears,  which  should  discour- 
age no  one,  it  seems  to  us  that  under  the  first  form  given  it  by  von 
Staudt,  projective  geometry  must  become  the  necessary  companion 
of  descriptive  geometry,  that  it  is  called  to  renovate  this  geometry 
in  its  spirit,  its  procedures,  and  its  applications. 

This  has  already  been  comprehended  in  many  countries,  and 
notably  in  Italy,  where  the  great  geometer  Cremona  did  not  disdain 
to  write  for  the  schools  an  elementary  treatise  on  projective  geometry. 

IX 

In  the  preceding  articles,  we  have  essayed  to  follow  and  bring  out 
clearly  the  most  remote  consequences  of  the  methods  of  Monge  and 
Poncelet.  In  creating  tangential  coordinates  and  homogeneous  coor- 
dinates, Pluecker  seemed  to  have  exhausted  all  that  the  method  of 
projections  and  that  of  reciprocal  polars  give  to  analysis. 

It  remained  for  him,  toward  the  end  of  his  life,  to  return  to  his 
first  researches  to  give  them  an  extension  enlarging  to  an  unexpected 
degree  the  domain  of  geometry. 


548  GEOMETRY 

Preceded  by  innumerable  researches  on  systems  of  straight  lines, 
due  to  Poinsot,  Moebius,  Chasles,  Dupin,  Malus.  Hamilton,  Krummer, 
Transon,  above  all  to  Cayley,  who  first  introduced  the  notion  of  the 
coordinates  of  the  straight,  researches  originating  perhaps  in  statics 
and  kinematics,  perhaps  in  geometrical  optics,  Pluecker's  geometry  of 
the  straight  line  will  always  be  regarded  as  the  part  of  his  work  Avhere 
are  met  the  newest  and  most  interesting  ideas. 

Pluecker  first  set  up  a  methodic  study  of  the  straight  line,  which 
already  is  important,  but  that  is  nothing  beside  what  he  discov 
ered.  It  is  sometimes  said  that  the  principle  of  duality  shows  that 
the  plane  as  well  as  the  point  may  be  considered  as  a  space  element. 
That  is  true;  but  in  adding  the  straight  line  to  the  plane  and  point 
as  possible  space  element,  Pluecker  was  led  to  recognize  that  any 
curve,  any  surface,  may  also  be  considered  as  space  element,  and  so 
was  born  a  new  geometry  which  already  has  inspired  a  great  number 
of  works,  which  will  raise  up  still  more  in  the  future. 

A  beautiful  discovery,  of  which  we  shall  speak  further  on,  has 
already  connected  the  geometry  of  spheres  with  that  of  straight  lines 
and  permits  the  introduction  of  the  notion  of  coordinates  of  a  sphere. 

The  theory  of  systems  of  circles  is  already  commenced;  it  will 
be  developed  without  doubt  when  one  wishes  to  study  the  representa- 
tion, which  we  owe  to  Laguerre,  of  an  imaginary  point  in  space  by  an 
oriented  circle. 

But  before  expounding  the  development  of  these  new  ideas  which 
have  vivified  the  infinitesimal  methods  of  Monge,  it  is  necessary  to  go 
back  to  take  up  the  history  of  branches  of  geometry  that  we  have 
neglected  until  now. 

X 

Among  the  works  of  the  school  of  Monge,  we  have  hitherto  con- 
fined ourselves  to  the  consideration  of  those  connected  with  -finite 
geometry;  but  certain  of  the  disciples  of  Monge  devoted  themselves 
above  all  to  developing  the  new  notions  of  infinitesimal  geometry 
applied  by  their  master  to  curves  of  double  curvature,  to  lines  of  curv- 
ature, to  the  generation  of  surfaces,  notions  expounded  at  least  in 
part  in  the  Application  de  V Analyse  a  la  Geometrie.  Among  these 
we  must  cite  Lancret,  author  of  beautiful  works  on  skew  curves,  and 
above  all  Charles  Dupin,  the  only  one  perhaps  who  followed  all  the 
paths  opened  by  Monge. 

Among  other  works,  we  owe  to  Dupin  two  volumes  Monge  would 
not  have  hesitated  to  sign:  Les  Developpements  de  Geometrie  pure, 
issued  in  1813,  and  Les  Applications  de  Geometrie  et  de  Mecanique, 
dating  from  1822. 

There  we  find  the  notion  of  indicatrix,  which  was  to  renovate, 
after  Euler  and  Meunier,  all  the  theory  of  curvature,  that  of  conjugate 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS    549 

tangents,  of  asymptotic  lines  which  have  taken  so  important  a  place 
in  recent  researches.  Nor  should  we  forget  the  determination  of  the 
surface  of  which  all  the  lines  of  curvature  are  circles,  nor  above  all 
the  memoir  on  triple  systems  of  orthogonal  surfaces  where  is  found, 
together  with  the  discovery  of  the  triple  system  formed  by  surfaces 
of  the  second  degree,  the  celebrated  theorem  to  which  the  name  of 
Dupin  wiU  remain  attached. 

Under  the  influence  of  these  works  and  of  the  renaissance  of  syn- 
thetic methods,  the  geometry  of  infinitesimals  retook  in  all  researches 
the  place  Lagrange  had  wished  to  take  away  from  it  forever. 

Singular  thing,  the  geometric  methods  thus  restored  were  to  receive 
the  most  vivid  impulse  in  consequence  of  the  publication  of  a  memoir 
which,  at  least  at  first  blush,  would  appear  connected  with  the  purest 
analysis;  we  mean  the  celebrated  paper  of  Gauss,  Disquisitiones 
generates  circa  superficies  curvas,  which  was  presented  in  1827  to  the 
Gottingen  Society,  and  whose  appearance  marked,  one  may  say, 
a  decisive  date  in  the  history  of  infinitesimal  geometry. 

From  this  moment,  the  infinitesimal  method  took  in  France  a  free 
scope  before  unknown. 

Frenet,  Bertrand,  Molins,  J.  A.  Serret,  Bouquet,  Puiseux,  Ossian 
Bonnet,  Paul  Serret,  develop  the  theory  of  skew  curves.  Liouville, 
Chasles,  Minding,  join  them  to  pursue  the  methodic  study  of  the 
memoir  of  Gauss. 

The  integration  made  by  Jacobi  of  the  differential  equation  of  the 
geodesic  lines  of  the  ellipsoid  started  a  great  number  of  researches. 
At  the  same  time  the  problems  studied  in  the  Application  de  V Analyse 
of  Monge  were  greatly  developed. 

The  determination  of  all  the  surfaces  having  their  lines  of  curvature 
plane  or  spheric  completed  in  the  happiest  manner  certain  partial 
results  already  obtained  by  Monge. 

At  this  moment,  one  of  the  most  penetrating  of  geometers,  ac- 
cording to  the  judgment  of  Jacobi,  Gabriel  Lame,  who,  like  Charles 
Sturm,  had  commenced  with  pure  geometry  and  had  already  made  to 
this  science  contributions  the  most  interesting  by  a  little  book  pub- 
lished in  1817  and  by  memoirs  inserted  in  the  Annates  of  Gergonne, 
utilized  the  results  obtained  by  Dupin  and  Binet  on  the  system  of 
confocal  surfaces  of  the  second  degree,  and,  rising  to  the  idea  of 
curvilinear  coordinates  in  space,  became  the  creator  of  a  wholly  new 
theory  destined  to  receive  in  mathematical  physics  the  most  varied 
applications. 

XI 

Here  again,  in  this  infinitesimal  branch  of  geometry  are  found  the 
two  tendencies  we  have  pointed  out  a  propos  of  the  geometry  of  finite 
quantities. 


550  GEOMETRY 

Some,  among  whom  must  be  placed  J.  Bertrand  and  O.  Bonnet, 
wish  to  constitute  an  independent  method  resting  directly  on  the 
employment  of  infinitesimals.  The  grand  Traite  de  Calcul  differ entiel, 
of  Bertrand,  contains  many  chapters  on  the  theory  of  curves  and 
of  surfaces,  which  are,  in  some  sort,  the  illustration  of  this  con- 
ception. 

Others  follow  the  usual  analytic  ways,  being  only  intent  to  clearly 
recognize  and  put  in  evidence  the  elements  which  figure  in  the  first 
plan.  Thus  did  Lame  in  introducing  his  theory  of  differential  'para- 
meters. Thus  did  Beltrami  in  extending  with  great  ingenuity  the 
employment  of  these  differential  invariants  to  the  case  of  two  inde- 
pendent variables,  that  is  to  say,  to  the  study  of  surfaces. 

It  seems  that  to-day  is  accepted  a  mixed  method  whose  origin  is 
found  in  the  works  of  Ribaucour,  under  the  name  perimorphie.  The 
rectangular  axes  of  analytic  geometry  are  retained,  but  made  mobile 
and  attached  as  seems  best  to  the  system  to  be  studied.  Thus  dis- 
appear most  of  the  objections  which  have  been  made  to  the  method 
of  coordinates.  The  advantages  of  what  is  sometimes  called  intrinsic 
geometry  are  united  to  those  resulting  from  the  use  of  the  regular 
analysis.  Besides,  this  analysis  is  by  no  means  abandoned;  the  com- 
plications of  calculation  which  it  almost  always  carries  with  it,  in  its 
applications  to  the  study  of  surfaces  and  rectilinear  coordinates,  usu- 
ally disappear  if  one  employs  the  notion  on  the  invariants  and  the 
covariants  of  quadratic  powers  of  differentials  which  we  owe  to  the 
researches  of  Lipschitz  and  Christoffel,  inspired  by  Riemann's  studies 
on  the  non-Euclidean  geometry. 

XII 

The  results  of  so  many  labors  were  not  long  in  coming.  The  notion 
of  geodesic  curvature  which  Gauss  already  possessed,  but  without 
having  published  it,  was  given  by  Bonnet  and  Liouville;  the  theory 
of  surfaces  of  which  the  radii  of  curvature  are  functions  one  of  the 
other,  inaugurated  in  Germany  by  two  propositions  which  would 
figure  without  disadvantage  in  the  memoir  of  Gauss,  was  enriched 
by  Ribaucour,  Halphen,  S.  Lie,  and  others,  with  a  multitude  of  propo- 
sitions, some  concerning  these  surfaces  envisaged  in  a  general  man- 
ner; others  applying  to  particular  cases  where  the  relation  between 
the  radii  of  curvature  takes  a  form  particularly  simple;  to  minimal 
surfaces  for  example,  and  also  to  surfaces  of  constant  curvature, 
positive  or  negative. 

The  minimal  surfaces  were  the  object  of  works  which  make  of 
their  study  the  most  attractive  chapter  of  infinitesimal  geometry. 
The  integration  of  their  partial  differential  equation  constitutes  one 
of  the  most  beautiful  discoveries  of  Monge;  but  because  of  the  im- 
perfection of  the  theory  of  imaginaries,  the  great  geometer  could  not 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS    551 

get  from  its  formulas  any  mode  of  generation  of  these  surfaces,  nor 
even  any  particular  surface.  We  will  not  here  retrace  the  detailed 
history  which  we  have  presented  in  our  Lecons  sur  la  theorie  des 
surfaces  ;  but  it  is  proper  to  recall  the  fundamental  researches  of 
Bonnet  which  have  given  us,  in  particular,  the  notion  of  surfaces 
associated  with  a  given  surface,  the  formulas  of  Weierstrass  which 
establish  a  close  bond  between  the  minimal  surfaces  and  the  functions 
of  a  complex  variable,  the  researches  of  Lie  by  which  it  was  estab- 
lished that  just  the  formulas  of  Monge  can  to-day  serve  as  founda- 
tion for  a  fruitful  study  of  minimal  surfaces. 

In  seeking  to  determine  the  minimal  surfaces  of  smallest  classes 
or  degrees,  we  were  led  to  the  notion  of  double  minimal  surfaces 
which  is  dependent  on  analysis  situs. 

Three  problems  of  unequal  importance  have  been  studied  in  this 
theory. 

The  first,  relative  to  the  determination  of  minimal  surfaces  in- 
scribed along  a  given  contour  in  a  developable  equally  given,  was 
solved  by  celebrated  formulas  which  have  led  to  a  great  number  of 
propositions.  For  example,  every  straight  traced  on  such  a  surface 
is  an  axis  of  symmetry. 

The  second,  set  by  S.  Lie,  concerns  the  determination  of  all  the 
algebraic  minimal  surfaces  inscribed  in  an  algebraic  developable, 
without  the  curve  of  contact  being  given.  It  also  has  been  entirely 
elucidated. 

The  third  and  the  most  difficult  is  what  the  physicists  solve  experi- 
mentally, by  plunging  a  closed  contour  into  a  solution  of  glycerine. 
It  concerns  the  determination  of  the  minimal  surface  passing  through 
a  given  contour. 

The  solution  of  this  problem  evidently  surpasses  the  resources  of 
geometry.  Thanks  to  the  resources  of  the  highest  analysis,  it  has 
been  solved  for  particular  contours  in  the  celebrated  memoir  of 
Riemann  and  in  the  profound  researches  which  have  followed  or 
accompanied  this  memoir. 

For  the  most  general  contour,  its  study  has  been  brilliantly  begun; 
it  will  be  continued  by  our  successors. 

After  the  minimal  surfaces,  the  surfaces  of  constant  curvature  at- 
tracted the  attention  of  geometers.  An  ingenious  remark  of  Bonnet 
connects  with  each  other  the  surfaces  of  which  one  or  the  other  of  the 
two  curvatures,  mean  curvature  or  total  curvature,  is  constant. 

Bour  announced  that  the  partial  differential  equation  of  surfaces 
of  constant  curvature  could  be  completely  integrated.  This  result 
has  not  been  secured;  it  would  seem  even  very  doubtful  if  we  con- 
sider a  research  where  S.  Lie  has  essayed  in  vain  to  apply  a  general 
method  of  integration  of  partial  differential  equations  to  the  particu- 
lar equation  of  surfaces  of  constant  curvature. 


552  GEOMETRY 

But,  if  it  is  impossible  to  determine  in  finite  terms  all  these  sur- 
faces, it  has  at  least  been  possible  to  obtain  certain  of  them,  char- 
acterized by  special  properties,  such  as  that  of  having  their  lines  of 
curvature  plane  or  spheric;  and  it  has  been  shown,  by  employing  a 
method  which  succeeds  in  many  other  problems,  that  from  every  sur- 
face of  constant  curvature  may  be  derived  an  infinity  of  other  surfaces 
of  the  same  nature,  by  employing  operations  clearly  defined  which 
require  only  quadratures. 

The  theory  of  the  deformation  of  surfaces  in  the  sense  of  Gauss 
has  been  also  much  enriched.  We  owe  to  Minding  and  to  Bour  the 
detailed  study  of  that  special  deformation  of  ruled  surfaces  which 
leaves  the  generators  rectilineal.  If  we  have  not  been  able,  as  has 
been  said,  to  determine  the  surfaces  applicable  on  the  sphere,  other 
surfaces  of  the  second  degree  have  been  attacked  with  more  success, 
and,  in  particular,  the  paraboloid  of  revolution. 

The  systematic  study  of  the  deformation  of  general  surfaces  of  the 
second  degree  is  already  entered  upon;  it  is  one  of  those  which  will 
give  shortly  the  most  important  results. 

The  theory  of  infinitesimal  deformation  constitutes  to-day  one  of 
the  most  finished  chapters  of  geometry.  It  is  the  first  somewhat 
extended  application  of  a  general  method  which  seems  to  have  a  great 
future. 

Being  given  a  system  of  differential  or  partial  differential  equations, 
suitable  to  determine  a  certain  number  of  unknowns,  it  is  advantage- 
ous to  associate  with  it  a  system  of  equations  which  we  have  called 
auxiliary  system,  and  which  determines  the  systems  of  solutions 
infinitely  near  any  given  system  of  solutions.  The  auxiliary  system 
being  necessarily  linear,  its  employment  in  all  researches  gives 
precious  light  on  the  properties  of  the  proposed  system  and  on  the 
possibility  of  obtaining  its  integration. 

The  theory  of  lines  of  curvature  and  of  asymptotic  lines  has  been 
notably  extended.  Not  only  have  been  determined  these  two  series 
of  lines  for  particular  surfaces  such  as  the  tetrahedral  surfaces  of 
Lame;  but  also,  in  developing  Moutard's  results  relative  to  a  par- 
ticular class  of  linear  partial  differential  equations  of  the  second 
order,  it  proved  possible  to  generalize  all  that  had  been  obtained  for 
surfaces  with  lines  of  curvature  plane  or  spheric,  in  determining  com- 
pletely all  the  classes  of  surfaces  for  which  could  be  solved  the  pro- 
blem of  spheric  representation. 

Just  so  has  been  solved  the  correlative  problem  relative  to  asymp- 
totic lines  in  making  known  all  the  surfaces  of  which  the  infinitesimal 
deformation  can  be  determined  in  finite  terms.  Here  is  a  vast  field 
for  research  whose  exploration  is  scarcely  begun. 

The  infinitesimal  study  of  rectilinear  congruences,  already  com- 
menced long  ago  by  Dupin,  Bertrand,  Hamilton,  Kummer,  has  come 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS   553 

to  intermingle  in  all  these  researches.  Ribaucour,  who  has  taken  in 
it  a  preponderant  part,  studied  particular  classes  of  rectilinear  con- 
gruences and,  in  particular,  the  congruences  called  isotropes,  which 
intervene  in  the  happiest  way  in  the  study  of  minimal  surfaces. 

The  triply  orthogonal  systems  which  Lame  used  in  mathematical 
physics  have  become  the  object  of  systematic  researches.  Cayley 
was  the  first  to  form  the  partial  differential  equation  of  the  third 
order  on  which  the  general  solution  of  this  problem  was  made  to 
depend. 

The  system  of  homofocal  surfaces  of  the  second  degree  has  been 
generalized  and  has  given  birth  to  that  theory  of  general  cyclides  in 
which  may  be  employed  at  the  same  time  the  resources  of  metric 
geometry,  of  projective  geometry,  and  of  infinitesimal  geometry. 
Many  other  orthogonal  systems  have  been  made  known.  Among 
these  it  is  proper  to  signalize  the  cyclic  systems  of  Ribaucour,  for 
which  one  of  the  three  families  admits  circles  as  orthogonal  trajecto- 
ries and  the  more  general  systems  for  which  these  orthogonal  trajec- 
tories are  simply  plane  curves. 

The  systematic  employment  of  imaginaries,  which  we  must  be 
careful  not  to  exclude  from  geometry,  has  permitted  the  connection 
of  all  these  determinations  with  the  study  of  the  finite  deformation 
of  a  particular  surface. 

Among  the  methods  which  have  permitted  the  establishment  of 
all  these  results,  it  is  proper  to  note  the  systematic  employment  of 
linear  partial  differential  equations  of  the  second  order  and  of  systems 
formed  of  such  equations.  The  most  recent  researches  show  that  this 
employment  is  destined  to  renovate  most  of  the  theories. 

Infinitesimal  geometry  could  not  neglect  the  study  of  the  two 
fundamental  problems  set  it  by  the  calculus  of  variations. 

The  problem  of  the  shortest  path  on  a  surface  was  the  object  of 
masterly  studies  by  Jacobi  and  by  Ossian  Bonnet.  The  study  of 
geodesic  lines  has  been  followed  up;  we  have  learned  to  determine 
them  for  new  surfaces.  The  theory  of  ensembles  has  come  to  permit 
the  following  of  these  lines  in  their  course  on  a  given  surface. 

The  solution  of  a  problem  relative  to  the  representation  of  two 
surfaces  one  on  the  other  has  greatly  increased  the  interest  of  dis- 
coveries of  Jacobi  and  of  Liouville  relative  to  a  particular  class  of 
surfaces  of  which  the  geodesic  lines  could  be  determined.  The  results 
concerning  this  particular  case  led  to  the  examination  of  a  new  ques- 
tion: to  investigate  all  the  problems  of  the  calculus  of  variations  of 
which  the  solution  is  given  by  curves  satisfying  a  given  differential 
equation. 

Finally,  the  methods  of  Jacobi  have  been  extended  to  space  of 
three  dimensions  and  applied  to  the  solution  of  a  question  which 
presented  the  greatest  difficulties:   the  study  of  properties  of  mini- 


554  GEOMETRY 

mum  appertaining  to  the  minimal  surface  passing  through  a  given 

contour. 

XIII 

Among  the  inventors  who  have  contributed  to  the  development  of 
infinitesimal  geometry,  Sophus  Lie  distinguishes  himself  by  many 
capital  discoveries  which  place  him  in  the  first  rank. 

He  was  not  one  of  those  who  show  from  infancy  the  most  char- 
acteristic aptitudes,  and  at  the  moment  of  quitting  the  University  of 
Christiania  in  1865,  he  still  hesitated  between  philology  and  mathe- 
matics. 

It  was  the  works  of  Pluecker  which  gave  him  for  the  first  time 
full  consciousness  of  his  true  calling. 

He  published  in  1869  a  first  work  on  the  interpretation  of  imagin- 
aries  in  geometry,  and  from  1870  he  was  in  possession  of  the  directing 
ideas  of  his  whole  career.  I  had  at  this  time  the  pleasure  of  seeing 
him  often,  of  entertaining  him  at  Paris,  where  he  had  come  with  his 
friend  F.  Klein. 

A -course  by  M.  Sylow  followed  by  Lie  had  revealed  to  him  all  the 
importance  of  the  theory  of  substitutions;  the  two  friends  studied 
this  theory  in  the  great  treatise  of  C.  Jordan;  they  were  fully  con- 
scious of  the  important  role  it  was  called  on  to  play  in  so  many 
branches  of  mathematical  science  where  it  had  not  yet  been  applied. 

They  have  both  had  the  good  fortune  to  contribute  by  their  works 
to  impress  upon  mathematical  studies  the  direction  which  to  them 
appeared  the  best. 

In  1870,  Sophus  Lie  presented  to  the  Academy  of  Sciences  of  Paris 
a  discovery  extremely  interesting.  Nothing  bears  less  resemblance 
to  a  sphere  than  a  straight  line,  and  yet  Lie  had  imagined  a  singular 
transformation  which  made  a  sphere  correspond  to  a  straight  line, 
and  permitted,  consequently,  the  connecting  of  every  proposition 
relative  to  straight  lines  with  a  proposition  relating  to  spheres,  and 
vice  versa. 

In  this  so  curious  method  of  transformation,  each  property  relative 
to  the  lines  of  curvature  of  a  surface  furnishes  a  proposition  relative 
to  the  asymptotic  lines  of  the  surface  attained. 

The  name  of  Lie  will  remain  attached  to  these  deep-lying  relations 
which  join  to  one  another  the  straight  line  and  the  sphere,  those  two 
essential  and  fundamental  elements  of  geometric  research.  He  de- 
veloped them  in  a  memoir  full  of  new  ideas  which  appeared  in  1872. 

The  works  which  followed  this  brilliant  debut  of  Lie  fully  con- 
firmed the  hopes  it  had  aroused.  Pluecker's  conception  relative  to 
the  generation  of  space  by  straight  lines,  by  curves  or  surfaces 
arbitrarily  chosen,  opens  to  the  theory  of  algebraic  forms  a  field 
which  has  not  yet  been  explored,  which  Clebsch  scarcely  began  to 
recognize  and  settle  the  boundaries  of.   But,  from  the  side  of  infini- 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  GEOMETRIC  METHODS    555 

tesimal  geometry,  this  conception  has  been  given  its  full  value  by 
Sophus  Lie.  The  great  Norwegian  geometer  was  able  to  find  in  it 
first  the  notion  of  congruences  and  complexes  of  curves,  and  after- 
ward that  of  contact  transformations  of  which  he  had  found,  for  the 
case  of  the  plane,  the  first  germ  in  Pluecker.  The  study  of  these 
transformations  led  him  to  perfect,  at  the  same  time  with  M.  Mayer, 
the  methods  of  integration  which  Jacobi  had  instituted  for  partial 
differential  equations  of  the  first  order;  but  above  all  it  threw  the 
most  brilliant  light  on  the  most  difficult  and  the  most  obscure  parts 
of  the  theories  relative  to  partial  differential  equations  of  higher 
order.  It  permitted  Lie,  in  particular,  to  indicate  all  the  cases  in 
which  the  method  of  characteristics  of  Monge  is  fully  applicable  to 
equations  of  the  second  order  with  two  independent  variables. 

In  continuing  the  study  of  these  special  transformations,  Lie  was 
led  to  construct  progressively  his  masterly  theory  of  continuous 
groups  of  transformations  and  to  put  in  evidence  the  very  important 
role  that  the  notion  of  group  plays  in  geometry.  Among  the  essential 
elements  of  his  researches,  it  is  proper  to  signalize  the  infinitesimal 
transformations,  of  which  the  idea  belongs  exclusively  to  him. 

Three  great  books  published  under  his  direction  by  able  and  de- 
voted collaborators  contain  the  essential  part  of  his  works  and  their 
applications  to  the  theory  of  integration,  to  that  of  complex  units  and 
to  the  non-Euclidean  geometry. 

XIV 

By  an  indirect  way  I  have  arrived  at  that  non-Euclidean  geometry 
the  study  of  which  takes  in  the  researches  of  geometers  a  place  which 
grows  greater  each  day. 

If  I  were  the  only  one  to  talk  with  you  about  geometry,  I  should 
take  pleasure  in  recalling  to  you  all  that  has  been  done  on  this  sub- 
ject since  Euclid  or  at  least  from  Legendre  to  our  days. 

Envisaged  successively  by  the  greatest  geometers  of  the  last  cen- 
tury, the  question  has  progressively  enlarged. 

It  commenced  with  the  celebrated  postulatum  relative  to  parallels; 
it  ends  with  the  totality  of  geometric  axioms. 

The  Elements  of  Euclid,  which  have  withstood  the  action  of  so 
many  centuries,  will  have  at  least  the  honor  before  ending  of  arous- 
ing a  long  series  of  works  admirably  enchained  which  will  contrib- 
ute, in  the  most  effective  way,  to  the  progress  of  mathematics,  at  the 
same  time  that  they  furnish  to  the  philosophers  the  most  precise  and 
the  most  solid  points  of  departure  for  the  study  of  the  origin  and  of 
the  formation  of  our  cognitions. 

I  am  assured  in  advance  that  my  distinguished  collaborator  will 
not  forget,  among  the  problems  of  the  present  time,  this  one,  which  is 
perhaps  the  most  important,  and  with  which  he  has  occupied  himself 


556  GEOMETRY 

with  so  much  success;  and  I  leave  to  him  the  task  of  developing  it 
with  all  the  amplitude  which  it  assuredly  merits. 

I  have  just  spoken  of  the  elements  of  geometry.  They  have  received 
in  the  last  hundred  years  extensions  which  must  not  be  forgotten. 
The  theory  of  polyhedrons  has  been  enriched  by  the  beautiful  dis- 
coveries of  Poinsot  on  the  star  polyhedrons  and  those  of  Moebius 
on  polyhedrons  with  a  single  face.  The  methods  of  transformation 
have  enlarged  the  exposition.  We  may  say  to-day  that  the  first  book 
contains  the  theory  of  translation  and  of  symmetry,  that  the  second 
amounts  to  the  theory  of  rotation  and  of  displacement,  that  the 
third  rest  on  homothety  and  inversion.  But  it  must  be  recognized 
that  it  is  due  to  analysis  that  the  Elements  have  been  enriched  by 
their  most  beautiful  propositions. 

It  is  to  the  highest  analysis  that  we  owe  the  inscription  of  regular 
polygons  of  seventeen  sides  and  analogous  polygons.  To  it  we  owe 
the  demonstrations,  so  long  sought,  of  the  impossibility  of  the  quad- 
rature of  the  circle,  of  the  impossibility  of  certain  geometric  con- 
structions with  the  aid  of  the  ruler  and  the  compasses;  and  to  it  finally 
we  owe  the  first  rigorous  demonstrations  of  the  properties  of  maxi- 
mum and  of  minimum  of  the  sphere.  It  will  belong  to  geometry  to 
enter  upon  this  ground  where  analysis  has  preceded  it. 

What  will  be  the  elements  of  geometry  in  the  course  of  the  cen- 
tury which  has  just  commenced?  Will  there  be  a  single  elementary 
book  of  geometry?  It  is  perhaps  America,  with  its  schools  free  from 
all  programme  and  from  all  tradition,  which  will  give  us  the  best  solu- 
tion of  this  important  and  difficult  question. 

Von  Staudt  has  sometimes  been  called  the  Euclid  of  the  nine- 
teenth century;  I  would  prefer  to  call  him  the  Euclid  of  projective 
geometry ;  but  is  projective  geometry,  interesting  though  it  may  be, 
destined  to  furnish  the  unique  foundation  of  the  future  elements? 

XV 

The  moment  has  come  to  close  this  over-long  recital,  and  yet  there 
is  a  crowd  of  interesting  researches  that  I  have  been,  so  to  say,  forced 
to  neglect. 

I  would  have  loved  to  talk  with  you  about  those  geometries  of 
any  number  of  dimensions  of  which  the  notion  goes  back  to  the  first 
days  of  algebra,  but  of  which  the  systematic  study  was  commenced 
only  sixty  years  ago  by  Cayley  and  by  Cauchy.  This  kind  of  researches 
has  found  favor  in  your  country  and  I  need  not  recall  that  our  illus- 
trious president,  after  having  shown  himself  the  worthy  successor 
of  Laplace  and  Le  Verrier,  in  a  space  which  he  considers  with  us  as 
being  endowed  with  three  dimensions,  has  not  disdained  to  publish, 
in  the  American  Journal,  considerations  of  great  interest  on  the 
geometries  of  n  dimensions. 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   GEOMETRIC  METHODS         557 

A  single  objection  can  be  made  to  studies  of  this  sort,  and  was 
already  formulated  by  Poisson:  the  absence  of  all  real  foundation,  of 
all  substratum  permitting  the  presentation,  under  aspects  visible  and 
in  some  sort  palpable,  of  the  results  obtained. 

The  extension  of  the  methods  of  descriptive  geometry,  and  above 
all  the  employment  of  Pluecker's  conceptions  on  the  generation  of 
space,  will  contribute  to  take  away  from  this  objection  much  of  its 
force. 

I  would  have  liked  to  speak  to  you  also  of  the  method  of  equi- 
pollences,  of  which  we  find  the  germ  in  the  posthumous  works  of 
Gauss,  of  Hamilton's  quaternions,  of  Grassmann's  methods,  and  in 
general  of  systems  of  complex  units,  of  the  analysis  situs,  so  inti- 
mately connected  mth  the  theory  of  functions,  of  the  geometry 
called  kinematic,  of  the  theory  of  abaci,  of  geometrography,  of  the 
applications  of  geometry  to  natural  philosophy  or  to  the  arts.  But 
1  fear,  if  I  branched  out  beyond  measure,  some  analyst,  as  has  hap- 
pened before,  would  accuse  geometry  of  wishing  to  monopolize 
everything. 

My  admiration  for  analysis,  grown  so  fruitful  and  so  powerful  in 
our  time,  would  not  permit  me  to  conceive  such  a  thought.  But  if 
some  reproach  of  this  sort  could  be  formulated  to-day,  it  is  not  to 
geometry,  it  is  to  analysis  it  would  be  proper,  I  believe,  to  address  it. 
The  circle  in  which  the  mathematical  studies  appeared  to  be  inclosed 
at  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth  century  has  been  broken  on  all 
sides. 

The  old  problems  present  themselves  to  us  under  a  new  form,  new 
problems  offer  themselves,  whose  study  occupies  legions  of  workers. 

The  number  of  those  who  cultivate  pure  geometry  has  become 
prodigiously  restricted.  Therein  is  a  danger  against  which  it  is  im- 
portant to  provide.  We  must  not  forget  that,  if  analysis  has  acquired 
means  of  investigation  which  it  lacked  heretofore,  it  owes  them  in 
great  part  to  the  conceptions  introduced  by  the  geometers.  Geometry 
must  not  remain  in  some  sort  entombed  in  its  triumph.  It  is  in  its 
school  we  have  learned;  our  successors  must  learn  never  to  be  blindly 
proud  of  methods  too  general,  to  envisage  the  questions  in  themselves 
and  to  find,  in  the  conditions  particular  to  each  problem,  perhaps 
a  direct  way  towards  a  solution,  perhaps  the  means  of  applying  in 
an  appropriate  manner  the  general  procedures  which  every  science 
should  gather. 

As  Chasles  said  at  the  beginning  of  the  Apercu  historique,  "The 
doctrines  of  pure  geometry  offer  often,  and  in  a  multitude  of  ques- 
tions, that  simple  and  natural  way  which,  penetrating  to  the  very 
source  of  the  truths,  lays  bare  the  mysterious  chain  which  binds  them 
to  each  other  and  makes  us  know  them  individually  in  the  way  most 
luminous  and  most  complete." 


558  GEOMETRY 

Cultivate  therefore  geometry,  which  has  its  own  advantages,  with- 
out wishing,  on  all  points,  to  make  it  equal  to  its  rival. 

For  the  rest,  if  we  were  tempted  to  neglect  it,  it  would  soon  find  in 
the  apphcations  of  mathematics,  as  it  did  once  before,  means  to  rise 
up  again  and  develop  itself  anew.  It  is  like  the  giant  Antaus  who 
recovered  his  strength  in  touching  the  earth. 


THE  PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY 

BY    DR.    EDWARD    KASNER 

[Edward  Kasner,  Instructor  in  Mathematics,  Columbia  University,  b.  New  York 
City,  1877.  B.S.  CoUege  of  the  City  of  New  York,  1896;  A.M.  Columbia 
University,  1899;  Pli.D.  ifeid.  1899.  Post-graduate,  Fellow  in  Mathematics, 
Columbia  University,  1897-99  ;  Student,  University  of  Gottingen,  1899— 
1900;  Tutor  in  Mathematics,  Columbia  University,  1900-05;  Instructor, 
1905;  Member  American  Mathematical  Society;  Fellow  American  Associa- 
tion for  Advancement  of  Science.  Associate  editor.  Transactions  American 
Mathematical  Society.] 

In  spite  of  the  richness  and  power  of  recent  geometry,  it  is  notice- 
able that  the  geometer  himself  has  become  more  modest.  It  was  the 
ambition  of  Descartes  and  Leibnitz  to  discover  universal  methods, 
applicable  to  all  conceivable  questions;  later,  the  Ausdehnungslehre 
of  Grassmann  and  the  quaternion  theory  of  Hamilton  were  believed 
by  their  devotees  to  be  ultimate  geometric  analyses;  and  Chasles 
attributed  to  the  principles  of  duality  and  homography  the  same 
role  in  the  domain  of  pure  space  as  that  of  the  law  of  gravitation 
in  celestial  mechanics.  To-day,  the  mathematician  admits  the  ex- 
istence and  the  necessity  of  many  theories,  many  geometries,  each 
appealing  to  certain  interests,  each  to  be  developed  by  the  most 
appropriate  methods;  and  he  realizes  that,  no  matter  how  large  his 
conceptions  and  how  powerful  his  methods,  they  will  be  replaced 
before  long  by  others  larger  and  more  powerful. 

Aside  from  the  conceivability  of  other  spaces  with  just  as  self- 
consistent  properties  as  those  of  the  so-called  ordinary  space,  such 
diverse  theories  arise,  in  the  first  place,  on  account  of  the  variety 
of  objects  demanding  consideration,  —  curves,  surfaces,  congruences 
and  complexes,  correspondences,  fields  of  differential  elements,  and 
so  on  in  endless  profusion.  The  totality  of  configurations  is  indeed 
not  thinkable  in  the  sense  of  an  ordinary  assemblage,  since  the  total- 
ity itself  would  have  to  be  admitted  as  a  configuration,  that  is,  an 
element  of  the  assemblage.  ■ 

However,  more  essential  in  most  respects  than  the  diversity  in 
the  material  treated  is  the  diversity  in  the  points  of  view  from  which 
it  may  be  regarded.  Even  the  simplest  figure,  a  triangle  or  a  circle, 
has  an  infinity  of  properties  —  indeed,  recalling  the  unity  of  the 
physical  world,  the  complete  study  of  a  single  figure  would  involve 
its  relations  to  all  other  figures  and  thus  not  be  distinguishable  from 
the  whole  of  geometry.  For  the  past  three  decades  the  ruling  thought 
in  this  connection  has  been  the  principle  (associated  with  the  names 
of  Klein  and  Lie)  that  the  properties  which  are  deemed  of  interest 
in  the  various  geometric  theories  may  be  classified  according  to  the 


560  GEOMETRY 

groups  of  transformations  which  leave  those  properties  unchanged. 
Thus  almost  all  discussions  on  algebraic  curves  are  connected  with 
the  group  of  displacements  (more  properly  the  so-called  principal 
group),  or  the  group  of  projective  transformations,  or  the  group  of 
birational  transformations;  and  the  distinction  between  such  theories 
is  more  fundamental  than  the  distinction  between  the  theories  of 
curves,  of  surfaces,  and  of  complexes. 

Historically,  the  advance  has  been,  in  general,  from  small  to  larger 
groups  of  transformations.  The  change  thus  produced  may  be  likened 
to  the  varying  appearance  of  a  painting,  at  first  viewed  closely  in  all 
its  details,  then  at  a  distance  in  its  significant  features.  The  analogy 
also  suggests  the  desirability  of  viewing  an  object  from  several  stand- 
points, of  studying  geometric  configurations  with  respect  to  various 
groups.  It  is  indeed  true,  though  in  a  necessarily  somewhat  vague 
sense,  that  the  more  essential  properties  are  those  invariant  under 
the  more  extensive  groups ;  and  it  is  to  be  expected  that  such  groups 
will  play  a  predominating  role  in  the  not  far  distant  future. 

The  domain  of  geometry  occupies  a  position,  as  indicated  in  the 
programme  of  the  Congress,  intermediate  between  the  domain  of 
analysis  on  the  one  hand  and  of  mathematical  physics  on  the  other; 
and  in  its  development  it  continually  encroaches  upon  these  adjacent 
fields.  The  concepts  of  transformation  and  invariant,  the  algebraic 
curve,  the  space  of  n  dimensions,  owe  their  origin  primarily  to  the 
suggestions  of  analysis;  while  the  null-system,  the  theory  of  vector 
fields,  the  questions  connected  with  the  applicability  and  deforma- 
tion of  surfaces,  have  their  source  in  mechanics.  It  is  true  that  some 
mathematicians  regard  the  discussion  of  point  sets,  for  example, 
as  belonging  exclusively  to  the  theory  of  functions,  and  others  look 
upon  the  composition  of  displacements  as  a  part  of  mechanics. 
While  such  considerations  show  the  difficulty,  if  not  impossibility, 
of  drawing  strict  limits  about  any  science,  it  is  to  be  observed  that 
the  consequent  lack  of  definiteness,  deplored  though  it  be  by  the 
formalist,  is  more  than  compensated  by  the  fact  that  such  overlap- 
ping is  actually  the  principal  means  by  which  the  different  realms 
of  knowledge  are  bound  together. 

If  a  mathematician  of  the  past,  an  Archimedes  or  even  a  Descartes, 
could  view  the  field  of  geometry  in  its  present  condition,  the  first 
feature  to  impress  him  would  be  its  lack  of  concreteness.  There  are 
whole  classes  of  geometric  theories  which  proceed,  not  merely  with- 
out models  and  diagrams,  but  without  the  slightest  (apparent)  use 
of  the  spatial  intuition.  In  the  main  this  is  due,  of  course,  to  the 
power  of  the  analytic  instruments  of  investigation  as  compared 
with  the  purely  geometric.  The  formulas  move  in  advance  of  thought, 
while  the  intuition  often  lags  behind;  in  the  oft-quoted  words  of 
d'Alembert,  "  L'algebre  est  genereuse,  elle  donne  sou  vent  plus  qu'on 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      561 

hii  demande."  As  the  field  of  research  widens,  as  we  proceed  from 
the  simple  and  definite  to  the  more  refined  and  general,  we  naturally 
cease  to  picture  our  processes  and  even  our  results.  It  is  often  neces- 
sary to  close  our  eyes  and  go  forward  blindly  if  we  wish  to  advance 
at  all.  But  admitting  the  inevitableness  of  such  a  change  in  the 
spirit  of  any  science,  one  may  still  question  the  attitude  of  the  geo- 
meter who  rests  content  with  his  blindness,  who  does  not  at  least 
strive  to  intensify  and  enlarge  the  intuition.  Has  not  such  an  inten- 
sification and  enlargement  been  the  main  contribution  of  geometry 
to  the  race,  its  very  roison  d'etre  as  a  separate  part  of  mathematics, 
and  is  there  any  ground  for  regarding  this  service  as  completed? 

From  the  point  of  view  here  referred  to,  a  problem  is  not  to  be 
regarded  as  completely  solved  until  we  are  in  position  to  construct 
a  model  of  the  solution,  or  at  least  to  conceive  of  such  a  construction. 
This  requires  the  interpretation,  not  merely  of  the  results  of  a  geo- 
metric investigation,  but  also,  as  far  as  possible,  of  the  intermediate 
processes  —  an  attitude  illustrated  most  strikingly  in  the  works  of 
Lie.  This  duty  of  the  geometer,  to  make  the  ground  won  by  means 
of  analysis  really  geometric,  and  as  far  as  possible  concretely  intui- 
tive, is  the  source  of  many  problems  of  to-da}^,  a  few  of  which  will 
be  referred  to  in  the  course  of  this  address. 

The  tendency  to  generalization,  so  characteristic  of  modern  geo- 
metry, is  counteracted  in  many  cases  by  this  desire  for  the  concrete, 
in  others  by  the  desire  for  the  exact,  the  rigorous  (not  to  be  con- 
fused with  the  rigid).  The  great  mathematicians  have  acted  on  the 
principle  "Devinez  avant  de  demontrer,"  and  it  is  certainly  true 
that  almost  all  important  discoveries  are  made  in  this  fashion.  But 
while  the  demonstration  comes  after  the  discovery,  it  cannot  there- 
fore be  disregarded.  The  spirit  of  rigor,  which  tended  at  first  to  the 
arithmetization  of  all  mathematics  and  now  tends  to  its  exhibition 
in  terms  of  pure  logic,  has  always  been  more  prominent  in  analysis 
than  in  geometry.  Absolute  rigor  may  be  unattainable,  but  it  can- 
not be  denied  that  much  remains  to  be  done  by  the  geometers,  judg- 
ing even  by  elementary  standards.  We  need  refer  only  to  the  loose 
proofs  based  upon  the  invaluable  but  insufficient  enumeration  of 
constants,  the  so-called  principle  of  the  conservation  of  number,  and 
the  discussions  which  confine  themselves  to  the  "general  case." 
Examples  abound  in  every  field  of  geometry.  The  theorem  announced 
by  Chasles  concerning  the  number  of  conies  satisfying  five  arbitrary 
conditions  was  proved  by  such  masters  as  Clebsch  and  Halphen  be- 
fore examples  invalidating  the  result  were  devised.  Picard  recently 
called  attention  to  the  need  of  a  new  proof  of  Noether's  theorem  that 
upon  the  general  algebraic  surface  of  degree  greater  than  three  every 
algebraic  curve  is  a  complete  intersection  T\dth  another  algebraic 
surface.     The  considerations  given  by  Noether  render  the  result 


562  GEOMETRY 

highly  probable,  but  do  not  constitute  a  complete  proof;  while  the 
exact  meaning  of  the  term  general  can  be  determined  only  from 
the  context. 

The  reaction  against  such  loose  methods  is  represented  by  Study  * 
in  algebraic  geometry,  and  Hilbert  in  differential  geometry.  The 
tendency  of  a  considerable  portion  of  recent  work  is  towards  the 
exhaustive  treatment  of  definite  questions,  including  the  considera- 
tion of  the  special  or  degenerate  cases  ordinarily  passed  over  as 
unimportant.  Another  aspect  of  the  same  tendency  is  the  discussion 
of  converses  of  familiar  problems,  with  the  object  of  obtaining  con- 
ditions at  once  necessary  and  sufficient,  that  is,  completely  character- 
istic results.^ 

Another  set  of  problems  is  suggested  by  the  relation  of  geometry 
to  physics.  It  is  the  duty  of  the  geometer  to  abstract  from  the  physical 
sciences  those  domains  which  may  be  expressed  in  terms  of  pure 
space,  to  study  the  geometric  foundations  (or,  as  some  would  put  it, 
the  skeletons)  of  the  various  branches  of  mechanics  and  physics. 
Most  of  the  actual  advance,  it  is  true,  has  hitherto  come  from  the 
physicists  themselves,  but  undoubtedly  the  time  has  arrived  for 
more  systematic  discussions  by  the  mathematicians.  In  addition  to 
the  importance  which  is  due  to  possible  applications  of  such  work, 
it  is  to  be  noticed  that  we  meet,  in  this  way,  configurations  as  inter- 
esting and  remarkable  as  those  created  by  the  geometer's  imagina- 
tion. Even  in  this  field,  one  is  tempted  to  remark,  truth  is  stranger 
than  fiction. 

We  have  now  considered,  briefly  and  inadequately,  some  of  the 
leading  ideals  and  influences  which  are  at  work  towards  both  the 
"wddening  and  the  deepening  of  geometry  in  general;  and  turn  to  our 
proper  topic,  a  survey  of  the  leading  problems  or  groups  of  problems 
in  certain  selected  (but  it  is  hoped  representative)  fields  of  contem- 
poraneous investigation. 

Foundations 

The  most  striking  development  of  geometry  during  the  past  decade 
relates  to  the  critical  revision  of  its  foundations,  more  precisely,  its 
logical  foundations.    There  are,  of  course,  other  points  of  view,  for 

^  "  [Es  ist  eine]  tief  eingewurzelte  Gewohnheit  vieler  Geometer,  Satze  zu  formu- 
lieren,  die  'im  allgemeinen '  gelten  sollen.  d.  h.  einen  klaren  Sinn  iiberhaupt  nicht 
haben,  zudem  noch  haufig  als  allgemein  giiltig  hingestellt  oder  mangelhaft  be- 
grundet  werden.  [Dies  Verfahren  mrd],  trotz  etwanigen  Verweisungen  auf  Trager 
sehr  beriihmter  Nam  en,  spateren  Gesclilechtern  sicher  als  ganz  unzulassig  erschei- 
nen,  scheint  aber  in  unserem  'kritischen'  Zeitalter  von  vielen  als  eine  berechtigte 
Eigenttimlichkeit  der  Geometrie  betrachtet  zu  werden  .  .  ."  Jakr.  Deut.  Math.- 
Ver.,  vol.  XI  (1902),  p.  100. 

^  As  an  example  may  be  mentioned  the  theorem  of  Malus  and  Dupin,  known 
for  almost  a  century,  that  the  rays  emanating  from  a  point  are  converted,  by  any 
refraction,  into  a  normal  congruence.  Quite  recently,  Levi-Civitta  succeeded  in 
sho-^nng  that  this  property  is  characteristic;  that  is,  any  normal  congruence  may 
be  refracted  into  a  bundle. 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      563 

example,  the  physical,  the  physiological,  the  psychological,  the  meta- 
physical, but  the  interest  of  mathematicians  has  been  confined  to  the 
purely  logical  aspect.  The  main  results  in  this  direction  are  due  to 
Peano  and  his  co-workers;  but  the  whole  field  was  first  brought 
prominently  to  the  attention  of  the  mathematical  world  by  the 
appearance,  five  years  ago,  of  Hilbert's  elegant  Festschrift. 

The  central  problem  is  to  lay  down  a  system  of  primitive  (unde- 
fined) concepts  or  symbols  and  primitive  (unproved)  propositions 
or  postulates,  from  which  the  whole  body  of  geometry  (that  is,  the 
geometry  considered)  shall  follow  by  purely  deductive  processes. 
No  appeal  to  intuition  is  then  necessary.  "  We  might  put  the  axioms 
into  a  reasoning  apparatus  like  the  logical  machine  of  Stanley  Jevons, 
and  see  all  geometry  come  out  of  it"  (Poincare).  Such  a  system  of 
concepts  and  postulates  may  be  obtained  in  a  great  (indeed  end- 
less) variety  of  ways:  the  main  question,  at  present,  concerns  the 
comparison  of  various  systems,  and  the  possibility  of  imposing  lim- 
itations so  as  to  obtain  a  unique  and  perhaps  simplest  basis. 

The  first  requirement  of  a  system  is  that  it  shall  be  consistent. 
The  postulates  must  be  compatible  with  one  another.  No  one  has  yet 
deduced  contradictory  results  from  the  axioms  of  Euclid,  but  what 
is  our  guarantee  that  this  will  not  happen  in  the  future?  The  only 
method  of  answering  this  question  which  has  suggested  itself  is  the 
exhibition  of  some  object  (whose  existence  is  admitted)  which  fulfills 
the  conditions  imposed  by  the  postulates.  Hilbert  succeeded  in  con- 
structing such  an  ideal  object  out  of  numbers;  but  remarks  that  the 
difficulty  is  merely  transferred  to  the  field  of  arithmetic.  The  most 
far-reaching  result  is  the  definition  of  number  in  terms  of  logical 
classes  as  given  by  Pieri  and  Russell;  but  no  general  agreement  is 
yet  to  be  expected  in  these  discussions.  Will  the  ultimate  conclu- 
sion be  the  impossibility  of  a  direct  proof  of  compatibility? 

More  accessible  is  the  question  concerning  the  independence  of 
postulates  (and  the  analogous  question  of  the  irreducibility  of  con- 
cepts). Most  of  the  work  of  the  last  few  years  has  been  concentrated 
on  this  point.  In  Hilbert's  original  system  the  various  groups  of 
axioms  (relating  respectively  to  combination,  order,  parallels,  con- 
gruence, and  continuity)  are  shown  to  be  independent,  but  the  dis- 
cussion is  not  carried  out  completely  for  the  individual  axioms.  In 
Dr.  Veblen's  recently  published  system  of  twelve  postulates,  each 
is  proved  independent  of  the  remaining  eleven.^  This  marks  an  ad- 
vance, but,  of  course,  it  does  not  terminate  the  problem.  In  what 
respect  does  a  group  o'f  propositions  differ  from  what  is  termed  a 
single  proposition?  Is  it  possible  to  define  the  notion  of  an  absolutely 
simple  postulate?  The  statement  that  any  two  points  determine  a 
straight  line  involves  an  infinity  of  statements,  and  its  fulfillment  for 
'  Trans.  Amer.  Math.  Soc,  vol.  v  (1904). 


564  GEOMETRY 

certain  pairs  of  points  may  necessitate  its  fulfillment  for  all  pairs. 
If  in  Euclid's  system  the  postulate  of  parallels  is  replaced  by  the 
postulate  concerning  the  sum  of  the  angles  of  a  triangle,  a  well-known 
example  of  such  a  reduction  is  obtained;  for  it  is  sufficient  to  as- 
sume the  new  postulate  for  a  single  triangle,  the  general  result  being 
then  deducible.  As  other  examples  we  may  mention  Peano's  reduc- 
tion of  the  Euclidean  definition  of  the  plane;  and  the  definition  of 
a  collineation  which  demands,  instead  of  the  conversion  of  all  straight 
lines  into  straight  lines,  the  existence  of  four  simply  infinite  systems 
of  such  straight  lines/ 

These  examples  illustrate  the  difficulty,  if  not  the  impossibility, 
of  formulating  a  really  fundamental,  that  is,  absolute  standard  of 
independence  and  irreducibility.  It  is  probable  that  the  guiding 
ideas  will  be  obtained  in  the  discussion  of  simpler  deductive  theories, 
in  particular,  the  systems  for  numbers  and  groups. 

Two  features  are  especially  prominent  in  the  actual  develop- 
ment of  the  body  of  geometry  from  its  fundamental  system.  First, 
the  consideration  of  what  may  be  termed  the  collateral  geometries, 
which  arise  by  replacing  one  of  the  original  postulates  by  its  opposite, 
or  otherwise  varying  the  system.  Such  theories  serve  to  show  the 
limitation  of  that  point  of  view  which  restricts  the  term  general 
geometry  (pangeometry)  to  the  Euclidean  and  non-Euclidean  geo- 
metries. The  variety  of  possible  abstract  geometries  is,  of  course, 
inexhaustible;  this  is  the  central  fact  brought  to  light  by  the  ex- 
hibition of  such  systems  as  the  non-Archimedean  and  the  non- 
arguesian.  In  the  second  place,  much  valuable  work  is  being  done  in 
discussing  the  various  methods  by  which  the  same  theorem  may 
be  deduced  from  the  postulates,  the  ideal  being  to  use  as  few  of  the 
postulates  as  possible.  Here  again  the  question  of  simplicity  (simplest 
proof),  though  it  baffles  analysis,  forces  itself  upon  the  attention. 

Among  the  minor  problems  in  this  field,  it  is  sufficient  to  consider 
that  concerning  the  relation  of  the  theory  of  volume  to  the  axiom  of 
continuity.  This  axiom  need  not  be  used  in  establishing  the  theory 
of  areas  of  polj^gons;  but  after  Dehn  and  others  had  proved  the  exist- 
ence of  polyhedra  having  the  same  volume  though  not  decomposable 
into  mutually  congruent  parts  (even  after  the  addition  of  congruent 
polyhedra),  it  was  stated  by  Hilbert,  and  deemed  evident  generally, 
that  reference  to  continuity  could  not  be  avoided  in  three  dimensions. 
In  a  recent  announcement  ^  of  Vahlen's  forthcoming  Abstrakte 
Geometrie  this  conclusion  is  declared  unsound.  It  seems  probable, 
however,  that  the  difference  is  merely  one  concerning  the  interpreta- 
tion to  be  given  to  the  term  continuity. 

'  Together  with  certain  continuity  assumptions.  Cf.  Bull.  Amer.  Math.  Soc, 
vol.  IX  (1903),  p.  545. 

2  Jahr.  Deut.  Math.-Ver.,  vol.  xiii  (1904),  p.  395, 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      565 

The  work  on  logical  foundations  has  been  confined  almost  entirely 
to  the  Euclidean  and  projective  geometries.  It  is  desirable,  however, 
that  other  geometric  theories  should  be  treated  in  a  similar  deductive 
fashion.  In  particular,  it  is  to  be  hoped  that  we  shall  soon  have 
a  really  systematic  foundation  for  the  so-called  inversion  geometry, 
dealing  with  properties  invariant  under  circular  transformations. 
This  theory  is  of  interest,  not  only  for  its  own  sake  and  for  its  appli- 
cations in  function  theory,  but  also  because  its  study  serves  to  free 
the  mind  from  what  is  apt  to  become,  without  some  check,  slavery  to 
the  projective  point  of  view. 

The  Curve  Concept  —  Analysis  Situs 

Although  curves  and  surfaces  have  constituted  the  almost  exclu- 
sive material  of  the  geometric  investigation  of  the  thirty  centu- 
ries of  which  we  have  record,  it  can  hardly  be  claimed  that  the  con- 
cepts themselves  have  received  their  final  analysis.  Certain  vague 
notions  are  suggested  by  the  naive  intuition.  It  is  the  duty  of  mathe- 
maticians to  create  perfectly  precise  concepts  which  agree  more  or 
less  closely  with  such  intuitions,  and  at  the  same  time,  by  the  reac- 
tion of  the  concepts,  to  refine  the  intuition.  The  problem,  evidently,  is 
not  at  all  determinate.  It  would  be  of  interest  to  trace  the  evolution 
which  has  actually  produced  several  distinct  curve  concepts  defining 
more  or  less  extensive  classes  of  curves,  agreeing  in  little  beyond  the 
possession  of  an  infinite  number  of  points. 

The  more  familiar  special  concepts  or  classes  of  curves  are  defined 
in  terms  of  the  corresponding  equation  y=f(x)  or  function  f(x). 
Such  are,  for  example:  (1)  algebraic  curves;  (2)  analytic  curves; 
(3)  graphs  of  functions  possessing  derivatives  of  all  orders;  (4)  the 
curves  considered  in  the  usual  discussions  of  infinitesimal  geometry, 
in  which  the  existence  of  first  and  second  derivatives  is  assumed; 
(5)  the  so-called  regular  curves  Math  a  continuously  turning  tangent 
(except  for  a  finite  number  of  corners);  (6)  the  so-called  ordinary 
curves  possessing  a  tangent  and  having  only  a  finite  number  of 
oscillations  (maxima  and  minima)  in  any  finite  interval;  (7)  curves 
with  tangents;  (8)  the  graphs  of  continuous  functions. 

How  far  are  such  distinctions  accessible  to  the  intuition?  Of 
course  there  are  limitations.  For  over  two  centuries,  from  Descartes 
to  the  publication  of  Weierstrass's  classic  example,  the  intuition  of 
mathematicians  declared  the  classes  (7)  and  (8)  to  be  identical.  Still 
later  it  was  found  that  such  extraordinary  (pathological  or  crinkly) 
curves  may  present  themselves  in  class  (7).  However,  even  here 
partially  successful  attempts  to  connect  with  intuition  have  been 
made  by  Wiener,  Hilbert,  Schoenflies,  Moore,  and  others. 

Let  us  consider  a  simpler  extension  in  the  field  of  ordinary  curves. 
If  the  function  jT (a:)  is  continuous  except  for  a  certain  value  of  x 


566  GEOMETRY 

where  there  is  an  ordinary  discontinuity,  this  is  indicated  by  a  break 
in  the  graph;  \if  is  continuous,  but  the  derivative y  has  such  a  dis- 
continuity, this  shows  itself  by  a  sharp  turn  in  the  curve;  if  the 
discontinuity  is  only  in  the  second  derivative,  there  is  a  sudden 
change  in  the  radius  of  curvature,  which  is,  however,  relatively 
difficult  to  observe  from  the  figure;  finally,  if  the  third  derivative 
is  discontinuous,  the  effect  upon  the  curve  is  no  longer  apparent. 
Does  this  mean  that  it  is  impossible  to  picture  it?  Does  it  not  rather 
indicate  a  limitation  in  the  usual  geometric  training  which  goes 
only  as  far  as  relations  expressible  in  terms  of  tangency  and  curva- 
ture? For  the  interpretation  of  the  third  derivative  it  is  necessary 
to  consider  say  the  osculating  parabola  at  each  point  of  the  curve : 
in  the  case  referred  to,  as  we  pass  over  the  critical  point,  the 
tangent  line  and  osculating  circle  change  continuously,  but  there  is 
a  sudden  change  in  the  osculating  parabola.  If  in  fact  our  intuition 
were  trained  to  picture  osculating  algebraic  curves  of  all  orders,  it 
would  detect  a  discontinuity  in  a  derivative  of  any  order.  A  partial 
equivalent  would  be  the  ability  to  picture  the  successive  evolutes 
of  a  given  curve;  a  complete  equivalent  would  be  the  picturing  of 
the  successive  slope  curves  y=f'{x),  y=f"{x),  etc.  All  this  requires, 
evidently,  only  an  increase  in  the  intensity  of  our  intuition,  not  a 
change  in  its  nature. 

This,  however,  would  not  apply  to  all  questions.  There  are  func- 
tions which,  while  possessing  derivatives  of  all  orders  (then  neces- 
sarily continuous),  are  not  analytic  (that  is,  not  expressible  by  power 
series).  What  is  it  that  distinguishes  the  analytic  curves  among  this 
larger  class?  Is  it  possible  to  put  the  distinction  in  a  form  capable 
of  assimilation  by  an  idealized  intuition?  In  short,  what  is  the 
reall}^  geometric  definition  of  an  analytic  curve  ?  * 

Much  recent  work  in  function  theory  has  had  for  its  point  of  de- 
parture a  more  general  basis  than  the  theory  of  curves,  namely,  the 
theory  of  sets  or  assemblages  of  points,  with  special  reference  to 
the  notions  of  derived  set  and  the  various  contents  or  areas.  The 
geometry  of  point  sets  must  indeed  be  regarded  as  one  of  the  most 
important  and  promising  in  the  whole  field  of  mathematics.  It 
receives  its  distinctive  character,  as  compared  with  the  general 
abstract  theory  of  assemblages  (Mengenlehre),  from  the  fact  that  it 
operates  not  with  all  one-to-one  correspondences,  but  with  the 
group  of  analysis  situs,  the  group  of  continuous  one-to-one  corre- 
spondences. From  the  point  of  view  of  the  larger  group,  there  is  no 
distinction  between  a  one-dimensional  and  a  two-  or  many-dimen- 
sional continuum  (Cantor).  This  is  still  the  case  if  the  correspondence 

^  One  method  of  attack  would  be  the  interpretation  of  Pringsheim's  condi- 
tions; this  requires  not  merely  the  individual  derivative  curves,  but  the  limit  of 
the  system. 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      567 

is  continuous  but  not  one-to-one  (Peano,  1890).  In  the  domain  of 
continuous  one-to-one  correspondence,  however,  spaces  of  different 
dimensions  are  not  equivalent  (Jiirgens,  1899). 

An  important  class  of  curves,  much  more  general  than  those 
referred  to  above,  consists  of  those  point  sets  which  are  equivalent 
(in  the  sense  of  analysis  situs)  to  the  straight  line  or  segment  of  a 
straight  line.  This  is  Hurwitz's  simple  and  elegant  geometric  form- 
ulation of  the  concept  originally  treated  analytically  by  Jordan, 
the  most  fundamental  curve  concept  of  to-day.  The  closed  Jordan 
curves  are  defined  in  analogous  fashion  as  equivalent  to  the  peri- 
meter of  a  square  (or  the  circumference  of  a  circle). 

A  curve  of  this  kind  divides  the  remaining  points  of  the  plane  into 
two  simply  connected  continua,  an  inside  and  an  outside.  The 
necessity  for  proof  of  this  seemingly  obvious  result  is  seen  from  the 
fact  that  the  Jordan  class  includes  such  extraordinary  types  as  the 
curve  with  positive  content  constructed  recently  by  Osgood.^  Such 
a  separation  of  the  plane  may,  however,  be  thought  about  by  other 
than  Jordan  curves:  the  concept  of  the  boundary  of  a  connected 
region  gives  perhaps  the  most  extensive  class  of  point  sets  which 
deserve  to  be  called  curve.  Schoenflies  proposes  a  definition  for  the 
idea  of  a  simple  closed  curve  which  makes  it  appear  as  the  natural 
extension,  in  a  certain  sense,  of  the  polygon;  a  perfect  set  of  points 
P  which  separates  the  plane  into  an  exterior  region  E  and  an  interior 
region  /  such  that  any  E  point  can  be  connected  with  any  I  point 
b}^  a  path  (Polygonstrecke)  having  only  one  point  in  common  with 
P.  This  is  in  effect  a  converse  of  Jordan's  theorem,  and  shows 
precisely  how  the  Jordan  curve  is  distinguished  from  other  types 
of  boundaries  of  connected  regions. 

These  discussions  are  mentioned  here  simply  as  aspects  of  a  really 
fundamental  problem:  th,e  revision  of  the  concepts  and  results  of 
that  division  of  geometry  which  has  been  variously  termed  analysis 
situs,  theory  of  connection,  topology,  geometry  of  situation  —  a 
revision  to  be  carried  out  in  the  light  of  the  theory  of  assemblages.^ 

Algebraic  Surfaces  and  Birational  Transformations 

After  the  demonstration  of  the  power  of  the  methods  based  upon 
projective  transformation,  —  the  chief  contribution  due  to  the 
geometers  of  the  first  half  of  the  nineteenth  century,  —  attempts 
were  made  to  introduce  other  types  of  one-to-one  correspondence  or 
transformation  into  algebraic  geometry;  in  particular  the  inversion 
of  William  Thomson  and  Liouville,  and  the  quadratic  transformation 
of  Magnus.  The  general  theory  of  such  Cremona  transformations 
was  inaugurated  by  the  Italian  geometer  in  his  memoir  Sulle  tras- 

1  Trans.  Amer.  Math.  Soc,  vol.  iv  (1903),  p.  107. 

^  Cf.  Schoenflies,  Math.  Annalen,  vols,  lviii,  lix  (1903,  1904). 


568  GEOMETRY 

formazioni  geometriche  delle  figure  piane,  piiblished  in  1863.  Within 
afewyearS;  Clifford,  Noether,  and  Rosanes,  working  independently, 
established  the  remarkable  result  that  every  Cremona  transforma- 
tion in  a  plane  can  be  decomposed  into  a  succession  of  quadratic 
transformations,  thus  bringing  to  light  the  fact  that  there  are  at 
bottom  only  two  types  of  algebraic  one-to-one  correspondence,  the 
homographic  and  the  quadratic.^ 

The  development  of  a  corresponding  theory  in  space  has  been  one 
of  the  chief  aims  of  the  geometers  of  Italy,  Germany,  and  England 
for  the  last  thirty  years,  but  the  essential  question  of  decomposition 
still  remains  unanswered.  Is  it  possible  to  reduce  the  general  Cremona 
transformation  of  space  to  a  finite  number  of  fundamental  types  ? 

In  its  application  to  the  study  of  the  properties  of  algebraic 
curves  and  surfaces,  the  theory  of  the  Cremona  transformation 
is  usually  merged  in  the  more  general  theory  of  the  birational  trans- 
formation. By  means  of  the  latter,  a  correspondence  is  established 
which  is  one-to-one  for  the  points  of  the  particular  figure  considered 
and  the  transformed  figure,  but  not  for  all  the  points  of  space.  In 
the  plane  theory  an  important  result  is  that  a  curve  with  the  most 
complicated  singularities  can,  by  means  of  Cremona  transformations;, 
be  converted  into  a  curve  whose  only  singularities  are  multiple 
points  with  distinct  tangents  (Noether);  furthermore,  by  means  of 
birational  transformations,  the  singularities  may  be  reduced  to  the 
very  simplest  type,  ordinary  double  points  (Bertini).  The  known 
theory  of  space  curves  is  also,  in  this  aspect,  quite  complete.  The 
analogous  problem  of  the  reduction  of  higher  singularities  of  a  sur- 
face has  been  considered  by  Noether,  Del  Pezzo,  Segre,  Kobb,  and 
others,  but  no  ultimate  conclusion  has  yet  been  obtained. 

One  principal  source  of  difficulty  is  that,  while  in  case  of  two 
birationally  equivalent  curves  the  correspondence  is  one-to-one 
without  exception,  on  the  other  hand,  in  the  case  of  two  surfaces, 
there  may  be  isolated  points  which  correspond  to  curves,  and  just 
such  irregular  phenomena  escape  the  ordinary  methods.  Again, 
not  onl}^  singular  points  require  consideration,  as  is  the  case  in  the 
plane  theory,  but  also  singular  lines,  and  the  points  may  be  isolated 
or  superimposed  on  the  lines.  Most  success  is  to  be  expected  from 
further  application  of  the  method  of  projection  from  a  higher  space 
due  to  Clifford  and  Veronese.  In  this  direction  the  most  important 
result  hitherto  obtained  is  the  theorem,  of  Picard  and  Simart,  that 
any  algebraic  surface  (in  ordinary  space)  can  be  regarded  as  the 
projection  of  a  surface  free  from  singularities  situated  in  five-dimen- 
sional space. 

_  *  Segre  recently  called  attention  to  a  case  where  the  usual  methods  of  discus- 
sion fail  to  apply;  the  proof  has  been  completed  by  Castelnuovo.  Cf,  Atii  di 
Torino,  vol.  xxxvi  (1901). 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      569 

A  question  which  awaits  solution  even  in  the  case  of  the  plane 
is  that  relating  to  the  invariants  of  the  group  of  Cremona  trans- 
formations proper.  The  genus  and  the  moduli  of  a  curve  are  unaltered 
by  all  birational  transformations,  but  the  problem  arises:  Are  there 
properties  of  curves  which  remain  unchanged  by  Cremona,  although 
not  by  other  birational  transformations  ?  From  the  fact  that 
birationally  equivalent  curves  need  not  be  equivalent  under  the 
Cremona  group,  it  would  seem  that  such  invariants  —  Cremona 
invariants  proper  —  do  exist,  but  no  actual  examples  have  yet  been 
obtained.  The  problem  may  be  restated  in  the  form:  What  are  the 
necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  which  must  be  fulfilled  by  two 
curves  if  they  are  to  be  equivalent  with  respect  to  Cremona  trans- 
formations? Equality  of  genera  and  moduli,  as  already  remarked,  is 
necessary  but  not  sufficient. 

The  invariant  theory  of  birational  transformations  has  for  its 
principal  object  the  study  of  the  linear  systems  of  point  groups 
on  a  given  algebraic  curve,  that  is,  the  point  groups  cut  out  by 
linear  systems  of  curves.  Its  foundations  were  implicitly  laid  by 
Riemann  in  his  discussion  of  the  equivalent  theory  of  algebraic  func- 
tions on  a  Riemann  surface,  though  the  actual  application  to  curves 
is  due  to  Clebsch.  Most  of  the  later  work  has  proceeded  along 
the  algebraic-geometric  lines  developed  by  Brill  and  Noether,  the 
promising  purely  geometric  treatment  inaugurated  by  Segre  being 
rather  neglected. 

The  extension  of  this  type  of  geometry  to  space,  that  is,  the  de- 
velopment of  a  systematic  geometry  on  a  fundamental  algebraic 
surface  (especially  as  regards  the  linear  systems  of  curves  situated 
thereon),  is  one  of  the  main  tasks  of  recent  mathematics.  The 
geometric  treatment  is  given  in  the  memoirs  of  Enriques  and  Castel- 
nuovo,  while  the  corresponding  functional  aspect  is  the  subject  of 
the  treatise  of  Picard  and  Simart  on  algebraic  functions  of  two 
variables,  at  present  in  course  of  publication. 

The  most  interesting  feature  of  the  investigations  belonging  in 
this  field  is  the  often  unexpected  light  which  they  throw  on  the 
inter-relations  of  distinct  fields  of  mathematics,  and  the  advantage 
derived  from  such  relations.  For  example,  Picard  (as  he  himself 
relates  on  presenting  the  second  volume  of  his  treatise  to  the  Paris 
Academy  a  few  months  ago)  ^  for  a  long  time  was  unable  to  prove 
directly  that  the  integrals  of  algebraic  total  differentials  can  be 
reduced,  in  general,  to  algebraic-logarithmic  combinations,  until 
finally  a  method  for  deciding  the  matter  was  suggested  by  a  theorem 
on  surfaces  which  Noether  had  stated  some  twenty  years  earlier. 
Again,  in  the  enumeration  of  the  double  integrals  of  the  second 
species,  Picard  arrived  at  a  certain  result,  which  was  soon  noticed 
^  Comptes  Rendus,  February  1,  1904. 


570  GEOMETRY 

to  be  essentially  equivalent  to  one  obtained  by  Castelnuovo  in  his 
investigations  on  linear  systems;  and  thus  there  was  established 
a  connection  between  the  so-called  numerical  and  linear  genera  of  a 
surface,  and  the  number  of  distinct  double  integrals.^ 

A  closely  related  set  of  investigations,  originating  with  Clebsch's 
theorems  on  intersections  and  Liouville's  on  confocal  quadrics,  may 
be  termed  the  "geometry  of  Abel's  theorem."  As  later  applications 
we  can  merely  mention  Humbert's  memoirs  on  certain  metric  pro- 
perties of  curves,  and  Lie's  determination  of  surfaces  of  translation. 

Investigations  in  analysis  have  often  suggested  the  introduc- 
tion of  new  types  of  configurations  into  geometry.  The  field  of  alge- 
braic surfaces  is  especially  fruitful  in  this  respect.  Thus,  while  in  the 
case  of  curves  (excluding  the  rational)  there  always  exist  integrals 
everywhere  finite,  this  holds  for  only  a  restricted  class  of  surfaces; 
their  determination  depends  on  the  solution  of  a  partial  differential 
equation  which  has  been  discussed  in  a  few  special  cases. 

In  addition  to  such  relations  between  analysis  and  geometry, 
important  relations  arise  between  various  fields  of  geometry.  Just 
as  an  algebraic  function  of  one  variable  is  pictured  by  either  a  plane 
curve  or  a  Riemann  surface  (according  as  the  independent  and  de- 
pendent variables  are  taken  to  be  real  or  complex),  so  an  algebraic 
function  of  two  independent  variables  may  be  represented  by  either 
a  surface  in  ordinary  space  or  a  Riemannian  four-dimensional  mani- 
fold in  space  of  five  dimensions.  In  the  case  of  one  variable,  the 
single  invariant  number  (deficiency  or  genus  p)  which  arises  is 
capable  of  definition  in  terms  of  the  characteristics  of  the  curve  or 
the  connectivity  of  the  Riemann  surface.  In  passing  to  two  variables, 
however,  it  is  necessary  to  consider  several  arithmetical  invariants 
—  just  how  many  is  an  unsettled  question.  For  the  algebraic  surface 
we  have,  for  instance,  the  geometric  genus  of  Clebsch,  the  numerical 
genus  of  Cayley,  and  the  so-called  second  genus,  each  of  which  maj^ 
be  regarded  as  a  generalization,  from  a  certain  point  of  view,  of  the 
single  genus  of  a  curve;  all  are  invariant  with  respect  to  birational 
transformation. 

The  other  geometric  interpretation,  by  means  of  a  Riemannian 
manifold,  has  rendered  necessary  the  study  of  the  analysis  situs  of 
higher  spaces.  The  connection  of  such  a  manifold  is  no  longer  ex- 
pressed by  a  single  number  as  in  the  case  of  an  ordinary  surface,  but 
by  a  set  of  two  or  more,  the  so-called  numbers  of  Betti  and  Riemann. 
The  detailed  theory  of  these  connectivities,  difiicult  and  delicate 
because  it  must  be  derived  with  little  aid  from  the  intuition,  has  been 
made  the  subject  of  an  extensive  series  of  memoirs  by  Poincare. 

From  the  point  of  view  of  analysis,  the  chief  interest  in  these 
investigations  is  the  fact  that  the  connectivities  are  related  to  the 
^  Comptes  Rendus,  February  22,  1904. 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      571 

number  of  integrals  of  certain  types.  The  chief  problem  for  the 
geometer,  however,  is  the  discovery  of  the  precise  relations  between 
the  connectivities  of  the  Riemann  manifold  and  the  various  genera 
of  the  algebraic  surface.  That  relations  do  exist  between  such  di- 
verse geometries  —  the  one  operating  with  all  continuous,  the  other 
with  the  algebraic,  one-to-one  correspondence  —  is  one  of  the  most 
striking  results  of  recent  mathematics. 

Geometry  of  Multiple  Forms 

For  some  time  after  its  origin,  the  linear  invariant  theory  of 
Boole,  Cayley,  and  Sylvester  confined  itself  to  forms  containing  a 
single  set  of  variables.  The  needs  of  both  analysis  and  geometry, 
however,  have  emphasized  the  importance  and  the  necessity  of 
further  development  of  the  theory  of  forms  containing  two  or  more 
sets  of  variables  (of  the  same  or  different  type),  so-called  multiple 
forms. 

In  the  plane  we  have  both  point  coordinates  (x)  and  line  coor- 
dinates (u).  A  form  in  x  corresponds  to  a  point  curve  (locus),  a 
form  in  w  to  a  line  curve  (envelope),  and  a  form  involving  both  x 
and  u  to  &  connex.  The  latter  was  introduced  into  geometry,  some 
thirty  years  ago,  by  Clebsch,  the  suggestion  coming  from  the  fact 
that,  even  in  the  study  of  a  simple  form  in  x,  covariants  in  x  and  u 
present  themselves,  so  that  it  seemed  desirable  to  deal  with  such 
forms  ab  initio. 

Passing  to  space,  we  meet  three  simple  elements,  the  point  (x), 
the  plane  (u),  and  the  line  (p).  Forms  in  a  single  set  of  variables 
represent,  respectively,  a  surface  as  point  locus,  a  surface  as  plane 
envelope,  and  a  complex  of  lines.  The  compound  elements  composed 
of  two  simple  elements  are  the  point-plane,  the  point-line,  and  the 
plane-line.  The  first  type,  leading  to  point-plane  connexes,  has  been 
studied  extensively  during  the  past  few  years;  the  second  to  a  more 
limited  degree;  the  third  is  merely  the  dual  of  the  second.  To  com- 
plete the  series,  the  case  of  the  point-line-plane  as  element,  or  forms 
involving  x,  u,  and  p,  requires  investigation. 

In  the  corresponding  w-dimensional  theory  it  is  necessary  to  take 
account  of  n  simple  elements  and  the  various  compound  elements 
formed  by  their  combinations. 

The  importance  of  such  work  is  twofold:  First,  on  account  of 
connection  with  the  algebra  of  invariants.  A  fundamental  theorem 
of  Clebsch  states  that,  in  the  investigation  of  complete  systems  of 
comitants,  it  is  sufficient  to  consider  forms  involving  not  more  than 
one  set  of  variables  of  each  type :  if  in  the  given  forms  the  types  are 
involved  in  any  manner,  it  is  possible  to  find  an  equivalent  reduced 
system  of  the  kind  described.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  impossible 
to  reduce  the  system  further,  so  that  the  introduction  of  the  n  types 


572  GEOMETRY 

of  variables  is  necessary  for  the  algebraically  complete  discussion. 
Geometry  must  accordingly  extend  itself  to  accommodate  the 
configurations  defined  by  the  new  elements. 

Second,  on  account  of  connection  with  the  theory  of  differential 
equations.  The  ordinary  plane  connex  in  x,  u,  assigns  to  each  point 
of  the  plane  a  certain  number  of  directions  (represented  by  the 
tangents  drawn  to  the  corresponding  curve),  and  thus  gives  rise  to 
an  (algebraic)  differential  equation  of  the  first  order  in  two  variables; 
the  point-plane  connex  in  space,  associating  with  each  point  a  single 
infinity  of  incident  planes,  defines  a  partial  differential  equation 
of  the  first  order;  the  point-line  connex  yields  a  Monge  equation. 
The  point-line-plane  case  has  not  yet  been  interpreted  from  this 
point  of  view. 

One  special  problem  in  this  field  deserves  mention,  on  account  of  its 
many  applications.  This  is  the  study  of  the  system  composed  of  a 
quadric  form  in  any  number  of  variables  and  a  bilinear  form  in  con- 
tragredient  variables,  that  is,  a  quadric  manifold  and  an  arbitrary 
(not  merely  automorphic)  collineation  in  n-space.  For  n  =  6,  for 
example,  this  corresponds  to  the  general  linear  transformation  of 
line  or  sphere  coordinates. 

In  addition  to  forms  containing  variables  of  different  types,  the 
forms  involving  several  sets  of  variables  of  the  same  type  require 
consideration.  Forms  in  two  sets  of  line  coordinates  present  them- 
selves in  connection  with  the  pfaffian  problem  of  differential  systems. 
The  main  interest  attaches,  however,  to  forms  in  sets  of  point  coor- 
dinates, since  it  is  these  which  occur  in  the  theory  of  contact  trans- 
formations and  of  multiple  correspondences.  For  example,  while 
the  ordinary  homography  on  a  line  is  represented  by  a  bilinear  form 
in  binary  variables,  the  trilinear  form  in  similar  variables  gives  rise 
to  a  new  geometric  variety,  the  so-called  homography  of  the  second 
class  (associating  with  any  two  points  a  unique  third  point),  which 
has  applications  to  the  generation  of  cubic  surfaces  and  to  the  con- 
structions at  the  basis  of  photogrammetry.  The  theory  of  multilinear 
forms  in  general  deserves  more  attention  than  it  has  yet  received. 

Other  important  problems,  connected  with  the  geometric  phases  of 
linear  invariant  theory,  can  merely  be  mentioned:  (1)  The  general 
geometric  interpretation  of  what  appears  algebraically  as  the  sim- 
plest projective  relation,  namely,  apolarity.  (2)  The  invariant  dis- 
cussion of  the  simpler  discontinuous  varieties,  for  example,  the  poly- 
gon considered  as  w-point  or  as  n-line.^  (3)  The  establishment  of  a 
system  of  forms  corresponding  to  the  general  space  curve.  (4)  The 
study  of  the  properties  and  the  groups  of  the  configurations  cor- 

^  Cf.  F.  Morley  "On  the  geometry  whose  element  is  the  3-point  of  a  plane," 
Trans.  Amer.  Math.  Soc,  vol.  v  (1904).  E.  Study  in  his  Geometrie  der  Dynamen 
develops  a  new  foundation  for  kinematics  by  employing  as  element  the  Soma  or 
trirectangular  trihedron. 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      573 

responding  in  hyperspace  to  the  simpler  systems  of  invariants.  (5) 
Complete  systems  of  orthogonal  or  metric  invariants  for  the  simpler 
curves.  ^ 

Transcendental  Curves 

To  reduce  to  systematic  order  the  chaos  of  non-algebraic  curves 
has  been  the  aspiration  of  many  a  mathematician;  bat,  despite  all 
efforts,  we  have  no  theory  comparable  with  that  of  algebraic  curves. 
The  very  vagueness  and  apparent  hopelessness  of  the  question  is 
apt  to  repel  the  modern  mathematician,  to  cause  him  to  return  to 
the  more  familiar  field.  The  resulting  concentration  has  led  to  the 
powerful  methods,  already  referred  to,  for  studying  algebraic  varie- 
ties. In  the  transcendental  domain,  on  the  other  hand,  we  have  a 
multitude  of  interesting  but  particular  geometric  forms,  —  some 
suggested  by  mechanics  and  physics,  others  derived  from  their  relation 
to  algebraic  curves,  or  by  the  interpretation  of  analytic  results  — 
a  few  thousands  of  which  have  been  considered  of  sufficient  importance 
to  deserve  specific  names.  ^  The  problem  at  issue  is  then  a  practical 
one  (comparable  with  corresponding  discussions  in  natural  history) : 
to  formulate  a  principle  of  classification  which  will  apply,  not  to  all 
possible  curves,  but  to  as  many  as  possible  of  the  usual  important 
transcendental  curves. 

The  most  fruitful  suggestion  hitherto  applied  has  come  from 
the  consideration  of  differential  equations:  almost  all  the  important 
transcendental  curves  satisfy  algebraic  differential  equations,  and 
these  in  the  great  majority  of  cases  are  of  the  first  order.  Hence  the 
need  of  a  systematic  discussion  of  the  curves  defined  by  any  algebraic 
equation  Fix,  y,  y')  =0,  the  so-called  panalgehraic  curves  of  Loria.  If 
F  is  of  degree  n  in  y'  and  of  degree  v  in  x,  y,  the  curve  is  said  to  belong 
to  a  system  with  the  characteristics  (n,  v) ,  and  we  thus  have  an  im- 
portant basis  for  classification.  Closely  related  is  the  theory  of  the 
Clebsch  connex;  this  figure,  it  is  true,  is  considered  as  belonging  to 
algebraic  geometry,  but  it  defines  (by  means  of  its  principal  coinci- 
dence) a  system  of  usually  transcendental  panalgebraic  curves. 

Both  points  of  view  appear  to  characterize  certain  systems  of 
curves  rather  than  individual  curves.  The  following  interpretation 
may  serve  as  a  simple  geometric  definition  of  the  curves  considered. 

With  any  plane  curve  C  we  may  associate  a  space  curve  in  this 
way:  at  each  point  of  C  erect  a  perpendicular  to  the  plane  whose 
length  represents  the  slope  of  the  curve  at  that  point;  the  locus  of 
the  end  points  of  these' perpendiculars  is  the  associated  space  curve 

^  Here  would  belong  in  particular  the  theory  of  algebraic  curves  based  on  link- 
ages. Little  advance  has  been  made  beyond  the  existence  theorems  of  Kempe 
and  Koenigs.  An  important  unsolved  problem  is  the  determination  of  the  link- 
age with  minimum  number  of  pieces  by  which  a  given  curve  can  be  described. 

^  Cf.  Loria,  Spezielle  Kurven,  Leipzig,  1902. 


574  GEOMETRY 

C.  Not  every  space  curve  is  obtained  in  this  way,  but  only  those 
whose  tangents  belong  to  a  certain  linear  complex.  If  C  is  algebraic 
so  is  C,  and  then  an  infinite  number  of  algebraic  surfaces  may  be 
passed  through  the  latter.  If  C  is  transcendental,  so  is  C ,  and 
usually  no  algebraic  surface  can  be  passed  through  it.  Sometimes, 
however;  one  such  algebraic  surface  F  exists.  (If  there  were  two, 
C  and  C  would  be  algebraic.)  It  is  precisely  in  this  case  that  the 
curve  C  is  panalgebraic  in  the  sense  of  Loria's  theory.  That  such  a 
curve  belongs  to  a  definite  system  is  seen  from  the  fact  that  while  the 
surface  F  is  unique,  it  contains  a  singly  infinite  number  of  curves 
whose  tangents  belong  to  the  linear  complex  mentioned,  and  the 
orthogonal  projections  of  these  curves  constitute  the  required  sj^stern. 
The  principal  problems  in  this  field  which  require  treatment  are: 
first,  the  exhaustive  discussion  of  the  simplest  systems,  correspond- 
ing to  small  values  of  the  characteristics  n  and  v  ;  second,  the  study  of 
the  general  case  in  connection  with  (1)  algebraic  differential  equa- 
tions, (2)  connexes,  and  (3)  algebraic  surfaces  and  linear  complexes. 

Natural  or  Intrinsic  Geometry 

In  spite  of  the  immediate  triumph  of  the  Cartesian  system  at  the 
time  of  its  introduction  into  mathematics,  rebellion  against  what 
may  be  termed  the  tyranny  of  extraneous  coordinates,  first  expressed 
in  the  Characteristica  geometrica  of  Leibnitz,  has  been  an  ever-present 
though  often  subdued  influence  in  the  development  of  geometry. 
Why  should  the  properties  of  a  curve  be  expressed  in  terms  of  x's 
and  ?/'s  which  are  defined  not  by  the  curve  itself,  but  by  its  relation 
to  certain  arbitrary  elements  of  reference?  The  same  curve  in  differ- 
ent positions  may  have  unlike  equations,  so  that  it  is  not  a  simple 
matter  to  decide  whether  given  equations  represent  really  distinct  or 
merely  congruent  curves.  The  idea  of  the  so-called  natural  or  in- 
trinsic coordinates  had  its  birth  during  the  early  years  of  the  nine- 
teenth century,  but  it  is  only  the  systematic  treatment  of  recent 
years  which  has  created  a  new  field  of  geometry. 

For  a  plane  curve  there  is  at  each  point  the  arc  s  measured  from 
some  fixed  point  on  the  curve,  and  the  radius  of  curvature  p;  these 
intrinsic  co5rdinates  are  connected  by  a  relation  p=f{s)  which  is 
precisely  characteristic  of  the  curve,  that  is,  the  curves  corresponding 
to  the  equation  differ  only  in  position.  There  is,  however,  still 
something  arbitrary  in  the  point  taken  as  origin.  This  is  eliminated 
by  taking  as  coordinates  p  and  its  derivative  8  taken  with  respect 
to  the  arc;  so  that  the  final  intrinsic  equation  is  of  the  form  8  =F(p). 
There  is  no  difficulty  in  extending  the  method  to  space  curves.  The 
two  natural  equations  necessary  are  here  T  =  (f)(p),  8=v//(p),  where 
p  and  T  are  the  radii  of  first  and  second  curvature  and  8  is  the  arc 
derivative  of  p. 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      575 

The  application  to  surfaces  is  not  so  evident.  Thus,  in  Cesaro's 
standard  work,  while  the  discussion  of  curves  is  consistently  in- 
trinsic, this  is  true  to  only  a  slight  extent  in  the  treatment  of  surfaces. 
The  natural  geometry  of  surfaces  is  in  fact  only  in  process  of  forma- 
tion. Bianchi  proposes  as  intrinsic  the  familiar  representation  by 
means  of  the  two  fundamental  quadratic  differential  forms;  but, 
although  it  is  true  that  the  surfaces  corresponding  to  a  given  pair 
of  forms  are  necessarily  congruent,  there  is  the  disadvantage,  arising 
from  the  presence  of  arbitrary  parameters,  that  the  same  surface 
may  be  represented  by  distinct  pairs  of  forms.  One  way  of  over- 
coming this  difficulty  is  to  introduce  the  common  feature  of  all  pairs 
corresponding  to  a  surface,  that  is,  the  invariants  of  the  forms:  in 
this  direction  we  may  cite  Ricci's  principle  of  covariant  differentia- 
tion and  Maschke's  recent  application  of  symbolic  methods. 

The  basis  of  natural  geometry  is,  essentially,  the  theory  of  differ- 
ential invariants.  Under  the  group  of  motions,  a  given  configuration 
assumes  go  ^  positions,  where  r  is  in  general  6,  but  may  be  smaller 
in  certain  cases.  The  r  parameters  which  thus  enter  in  the  analytic 
representation  may  be  eliminated  by  the  formation  of  differential 
equations.  The  aim  of  natural  geometry  is  to  express  these  differ- 
ential equations  in  terms  of  the  simplest  geometric  elements  of  the 
given  configuration. 

The  beginning  of  such  a  discussion  of  surfaces  was  given  by  Sophus 
Lie  in  1896  and  his  work  has  been  somewhat  simplified  by  Scheffers. 
As  natural  coordinates  we  may  take  the  principal  radii  of  curvature 
Ri,  Ri,  at  a  point  of  the  surface,  and  their  derivatives 


d. 


taken  in  the  principal  directions.  For  a  given  surface  (excluding 
the  Weingarten  class)  the  radii  are  independent,  and  there  are  four 
relations  of  the  form 

^22=/22(^l^    ■^2)- 

Conversely,  these  equations  are  not  satisfied  by  any  surfaces  except 
those  congruent  or  symmetric  to  the  given  surface. 

It  is  to  be  noticed  that  four  equations  thus  appear  to  be  necessary 
to  define  a  surface,  although  two  are  sufficient  for  a  twisted  curve. 
If  a  single  equation  in  the  above-mentioned  natural  coordinates  is 
considered,  it  is  not,  as  in  the  case  of  ordinary  coordinates,  charac- 
teristic: surfaces  not  congruent  or  symmetric  to  the  given  surface 
would  satisfy  the  equation.  The  apparent  inconsistency  which  arises 
is  removed,  however,  by  the  fact  that  the  four  natural  equations  are 


dR^ 

^        ^^1 

,                 dR2 

.           dR: 



^,0=  — 

o„  =  — 

0,,=  — ■ 

ds. 

''      ds. 

"       ds. 

"      ds. 

576  GEOMETRY 

dependent.*  It  is  just  this  that  makes  the  subject  difficult  as  com- 
pared with  the  theory  of  curves,  in  which  the  defining  equations  are 
entirely  arbitrary.  The  questions  demanding  treatment  fall  under 
these  two  headings:  first,  the  derivation  of  the  natural  equations 
of  the  familiar  types  of  surfaces,  and  second,  the  study  of  the  new 
types  that  correspond  to  equations  of  simple  form.  The  natural 
geometry  of  the  Weingarten  class  of  surfaces  requires  a  distinct  basis. 

The  fact  that  intrinsic  coordinates  are,  at  bottom,  differential 
invariants  with  respect  to  the  group  of  motions,  suggests  the  exten- 
sion of  the  same  idea  to  the  other  groups.  Thus  in  the  projective 
geometry  of  arbitrary  (algebraic  or  transcendental)  curves,  coor- 
dinates are  required  which,  unlike  the  distances  and  angles  ordin- 
arily used,  are  invariant  under  projection.  These  might,  for  exam- 
ple, be  introduced  as  follows.  At  each  point  of  the  general  curve  C, 
there  is  a  unique  osculating  cubic  and  a  unique  osculating  W  (self- 
projective)  curve.  Connected  with  each  of  these  osculating  curves 
is  an  absolute  projective  invariant  defined  as  an  anharmonic  ratio. 
These  ratios  may  then  be  taken  as  natural  projective  co5rdinates 
y  and  o),  and  the  natural  equation  on  the  curve  is  of  the  form 
y=J'((jj),  The  principal  advantage  of  such  a  representation  is  that 
the  necessary  and  sufficient  condition  for  the  equivalence  of  two 
curves  under  projective  transformations  is  simply  the  identity  of  the 
corresponding  equations. 

Returning  to  the  theory  of  surfaces,  natural  coordinates  may 
be  introduced  so  as  to  fit  into  the  so-called  geometry  of  a  flexible 
but  inextensible  surface,  originated  by  Gauss,  in  which  the  criterion 
of  equivalence  is  applicability,  or,  according  to  the  more  accurate 
phraseology  of  Voss,  isometry.  Intrinsic  coordinates  must  then  be 
invariant  with  respect  to  bending  (Biegungsinvariante) .  This  pro- 
perty is  fulfilled,  for  example,  by  the  Gaussian  curvature  k  and  the 
differential  parameters  connected  with  it  X=A  (k,  k),  fjL=A(K,  X), 
v=A{'K,  X),  all  capable  of  simple  geometric  interpretation.  The 
intrinsic  equations  are  then  of  the  form  ix=(f)(K,  X),  v=(f)(K,  X). 

A  pair  of  equations  of  this  kind  thus  represent,  not  so  much  a 
single  surface  S,  as  the  totality  of  all  surfaces  applicable  on  S  (or 
into  which  S  may  be  bent)  —  a  totality  which  is  termed  a  complete 
group  G,  since  no  additional  surfaces  are  obtained  when  the  same 
process  is  applied  to  any  member  of  the  totality.  The  discussion  of 
such  groups  is  ordinarily  based  on  the  first  fundamental  form  (repre- 
senting the  squared  element  of  length),  since  this  is  the  same  for 
isometric  surfaces;  though  of  course  it  changes  on  the  introduction 
of  new  parameters. 

The  simplest  example  of  a  complete  isometric  group  is  the  group 

^  The  three  relations  connecting  the  functions  /n,  /12,  hu  /22  have  been  worked 
out  recently  by  S.  Heller,  Math.  Annalen,  vol.  lviii  (1904). 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      577 

typified  by  the  plane,  consisting  of  all  the  developable  surfaces.  In 
this  case  the  equations  of  the  group  may  be  obtained  explicitly,  in 
terms  of  eliminations,  differentiations,  and  quadratures.  This  is, 
however,  quite  exceptional;  thus,  even  in  the  case  of  the  surfaces 
applicable  on  the  unit  sphere  (surfaces  of  constant  Gaussian  curv- 
ature +  1),  the  differential  equation  of  the  group  has  not  been 
integrated  explicitly.  In  fact,  until  the  year  1866,  not  a  single  case 
analogous  to  that  of  the  developable  surfaces  was  discovered.  Wein- 
garten,  by  means  of  his  theory  of  evolutes,  then  succeeded  in  deter- 
mining the  complete  group  of  the  catenoid  and  of  the  paraboloid 
of  revolution,  and,  some  twenty  years  later,  a  fourth  group  defined 
in  terms  of  minimal  surfaces. 

During  the  past  decade,  the  French  geometers  have  concentrated 
their  efforts  in  this  field  mainly  on  the  arbitrary  paraboloid  (and  to 
some  extent  on  the  arbitrary  quadric).  The  difficulties  even  in  this 
extremely  restricted  and  apparently  simple  case  are  great,  and  are 
only  gradually  being  conquered  by  the  use  of  almost  the  whole 
wealth  of  modern  analysis  and  the  invention  of  new  methods  which 
undoubtedly  have  wider  fields  of  application.  The  results  obtained 
exhibit,  for  example,  connections  with  the  theories  of  surfaces  of 
constant  curvature,  isometric  surfaces,  Backlund  transformations, 
and  motions  with  two  degrees  of  freedom.  The  principal  workers 
are  Darboux,  Goursat,  Bianchi,  Thybaut,  Cosserat,  Servant,  Gui- 
chard,  and  Raffy. 

Geometry  im  Grossen 

The  questions  we  have  just  been  considering,  in  common  with 
almost  all  the  developments  of  general  or  infinitesimal  geometry, 
deal  with  the  properties  of  the  figure  studied  im  Kleinen,  that  is, 
in  the  sufficiently  small  neighborhood  of  a  given  point.  Algebraic 
geometry,  on  the  other  hand,  deals  with  curves  and  surfaces  in  their 
entirety.  This  distinction,  however,  is  not  inherent  in  the  subject- 
matter,  but  is  rather  a  subjective  one  due  to  the  limitations  of  our 
analysis:  our  results  being  obtained  by  the  use  of  power  series  are 
valid  only  in  the  region  of  convergence.  The  properties  of  a  curve 
or  surface  (assumed  analytic)  considered  as  a  whole  are  represented 
not  by  means  of  function  elements,  but  by  means  of  the  entire  func- 
tions obtained  say  by  analytic  continuation. 

Only  the  merest  traces  of  such  a  transcendental  geometry  im 
Grossen  are  in  existence,  but  the  interest  of  many  investigators  is 
undoubtedly  tending  in  this  direction.  The  difficulty  of  the  problems 
which  arise  (in  spite  of  their  simple  and  natural  character)  and  the 
delicacy  of  method  necessary  in  their  treatment  may  be  compared 
to  the  corresponding  problems  and  methods  of  celestial  mechanics. 
The  calculation  of  the  ephemeris  of  a  planet  for  a  limited  time  is 


578  GEOMETRY 

a  problem  im  Kleinen,  while  the  discovery  of  periodic  orbits  and  the 
theory  of  the  stability  of  the  solar  system  are  typical  problems  im 
Grossen. 

The  principal  problems  in  this  field  of  geometry  are  connected 
with  closed  curves  and  surfaces.  Of  special  importance  are  the  inves- 
tigations relating  to  the  closed  geodesic  lines  which  can  be  drawn 
on  a  given  surface,  since  these  are  apt  to  lead  to  the  invention  of 
methods  applicable  to  the  wider  field  of  dynamics.  Geodesies  may 
in  fact  be  defined  dynamically  as  trajectories  of  a  particle  constrained 
to  the  surface  and  acted  upon  either  by  no  force  or  by  a  force  due  to 
a  force  function  U  whose  first  differential  parameter  is  expressible 
in  terms  of  U.  The  few  general  theorems  known  in  this  connection 
are  due  in  the  main  to  Hadamard  (Journal  de  Mathematiques,  1897, 
1898).  Thus,  on  a  closed  surface  whose  curvature  is  everywhere 
positive,  a  point  describing  a  geodesic  must  cross  any  existing  closed 
geodesic  an  infinite  number  of  times,  so  that,  in  particular,  two 
closed  geodesies  necessarily  intersect.^  On  a  surface  of  negative 
curvature,  under  certain  restrictions,  there  exist  closed  geodesies 
of  various  topological  types,  as  well  as  geodesies  which  approach 
these  asymptotically. 

As  regards  surfaces  all  of  whose  geodesies  are  closed,  the  investi- 
gations have  been  confined  entirely  to  the  case  of  surfaces  of  revo- 
lution, the  method  employed  being  that  suggested  by  Darboux  in 
the  Cours  de  Mecanique  of  Despeyrons.  Last  year  Zoll  ^  succeeded 
in  determining  such  a  surface  (beyond  the  obvious  sphere)  which 
differs  from  the  other  known  solutions  in  not  having  any  singularities. 
Analogous  problems  in  connection  with  closed  lines  of  curvature 
and  asymptotic  lines  will  probably  soon  secure  the  consideration 
they  deserve. 

A  problem  of  different  type  is  the  determination  of  applicability 
criteria  valid  for  entire  surfaces.  The  ordinary  conditions  (in  terms 
of  differential  parameters)  assert,  for  example,  the  applicability  of 
any  surface  of  constant  positive  curvature  upon  a  sphere;  but  the 
bending  is  actually  possible  only  for  a  sufficiently  small  portion  of  the 
surface.  A  spherical  surface  as  a  whole  cannot  be  applied  on  any 
other  surface,  that  is,  cannot  be  bent  without  extension  or  tearing. 
This  result  is  analogous  to  the  theorem  known  to  Euclid,  although 
first  proved  by  Cauchy,  that  a  closed  convex  polyhedral  surface  is 
necessarily  rigid.  Lagrange,  Minding,  and  Jellet  stated  the  result  for 
all  closed  convex  surfaces,  but  the  complete  discussion  is  due  to 
H.  Liebmann.^    The  theory  of  the  deformation  of  concave  surfaces 

^  In  a  paper  read  before  the  St.  Louis  meeting  of  the  American  Mathematical 
Society,  Poincar^  stated  reasons  which  make  very  probable  the  existence  of  at 
least  three  closed  geodesies  on  a  surface  of  this  kind. 

^  Math.  Annalen,  vol.  lvii  (1903). 

^  Gottingen  Nachrichten,  1899;  Math.  Annalen,  vols,  liii,  liv. 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      579 

is  far  more  complicated,  and  awaits  solution  even  in  the  case  of 
polyhedral  surfaces. 

Beltrami's  visualization  of  Lobachevsky's  geometry  by  pictur- 
ing the  straight  lines  of  the  Lobachevsky  plane  as  geodesies  on 
a  surface  of  constant  negative  curvature  is  well  known.  However, 
since  the  known  surfaces  of  this  kind,  like  the  pseudosphere,  have 
singular  Hues,  this  method  really  depicts  only  part  of  the  plane.  In 
fact  Hilbert  (Transactions  of  the  American  Mathematical  Society 
for  1900),  by  very  refined  considerations,  has  shown  that  an  analytic 
surface  of  constant  negative  curvature  which  is  everywhere  regular 
does  not  exist,  so  that  the  entire  Lobachevsky  plane  cannot  be 
depicted  by  any  analytic  surface.^  There  remains  undecided  the 
possibility  of  a  complete  representation  by  means  of  a  non-analytic 
surface.  The  partial  differential  equation  of  the  surfaces  of  negative 
constant  curvature  is  of  the  hyperbolic  type  and  hence  does  admit 
non-analytic  solutions.^  (This  is  not  true  for  surfaces  of  positive 
curvature,  since  the  equation  is  then  of  elliptic  type.)  The  discussion 
of  non-analytic  curves  and  surfaces  will  perhaps  be  one  of  the  really 
new  features  of  future  geometry,  but  it  is  not  yet  possible  to  indicate 
the  precise  direction  of  such  a  development.^ 

Other  theories  belonging  essentially  to  geometry  im  Grossen 
are  the  questions  of  analysis  situs,  or  topology,  to  which  reference  has 
been  made  on  several  occasions,  and  the  properties  of  the  very 
general  convex  surfaces  introduced  by  Minkowski  in  connection 
with  his  Geometrie  der  Zahlen. 

Systems  of  Curves  —  Differential  Equations 

Although  projective  geometry  has  for  its  domain  the  investigation 
of  all  properties  unaltered  by  collineation,  attention  has  been  con- 
fined almost  exclusively  to  the  algebraic  configuration,  so  that  pro- 
jective is  often  confused  with  algebraic  geometry.  To  the  more 
general  projective  geometry  belong,  for  example,  the  ideas  of  oscu- 
lating conic  of  an  arbitrary  curve  and  the  asymptotic  lines  of  an 
arbitrary  surface,  and  Mehmke's  theorem  which  asserts  that  when 
two  surfaces  touch  each  other,  the  ratio  of  their  Gaussian  curvatures 
at  the  point  of  contact  is  an  (absolute)  projective  invariant.  The 
field  for  investigation  in  this  direction  is  of  course  very  extensive, 
but  we  may  mention  as  a  problem  of  special  importance  the  deriva- 

^  The  entire  projective  plane,  on  the  other  hand,  can  be  so  depicted  on  a  sur- 
face devised  by  W.  Boy  {Inaugural  Dissertation,  Gottingen,  1901). 

^  According  to  Bernstein  (Math.  Annalen,  vol.  lix,  1904,  p.  72),  the  proof  given 
by  Lutkemeyer  (Inaugural  Dissertation,  Gottingen,  1902)  is  not  valid,  though 
the  conclusion  is  correct. 

^  Lebesgue  (Comptes  Rendus,  1900,  and  These,  1902)  has  examined  the  theory 
of  surfaces  applicable  on  a  plane  without  assuming  the  existence  of  derivatives 
for  the  defining  functions,  and  thereby  obtains  an  example  of  a  non-ruled  develop- 
able. 


580  GEOMETRY 

tion  of  the  conditions  for  the  projective  equivalence  of  surfaces  in 
terms  of  their  fundamental  quadratic  forms. 

Coordinate  with  what  has  just  been  stated,  that  general  configura- 
tions may  be  studied  from  the  projective  point  of  view,  is  the  fact 
that  algebraic  configurations  may  be  studied  in  relation  to  general 
transformation  theory.  One  may  object  that,  with  respect  to  the 
group  of  all  (analytic)  point  transformations,  the  algebraic  con- 
figurations do  not  form  a  hody,^  that  is,  are  not  converted  into 
algebraic  configurations;  but  such  a  body  is  obtained  by  adjoining 
to  the  algebraic  all  those  transcendental  configurations  which  are 
equivalent  to  algebraic.  As  this  appears  to  have  been  overlooked, 
it  seems  desirable  to  give  a  few  concrete  instances,  of  interest  in 
showing  the  effect  of  looking  at  familiar  objects  from  a  new  and 
more  general  point  of  view. 

As  a  first  example,  consider  the  idea  of  a  linear  system  of  plane 
curves.  In  algebraic  geometry,  a  linear  system  is  understood  to  be 
one  represented  by  an  equation  of  the  form 

where  the  X's  are  parameters  and  the  i^'s  are  polynomials  in  x,y.  On 
the  other  hand,  in  general  (infinitesimal)  geometry,  a  system  is  defined 
to  be  linear  when  it  can  be  reduced  (by  the  introduction  of  new 
parameters)  to  the  same  form  where  the  F's  are  arbitrary  functions. 
The  first  definition  is  invariant  under  the  projective  group;  the  sec- 
ond, under  the  group  of  all  point  transformations.  If  now  we  apply 
the  second  definition  to  algebraic  curves,  the  result  does  not  coincide 
with  that  given  by  the  first  definition.  Thus,  every  one-parameter 
system  is  linear  in  the  general  sense,  while  only  pencils  of  curves  are 
linear  in  the  projective  sense.  The  first  case  of  real  importance  is, 
however,  the  two-parameter  system,  since  here  each  point  of  view 
gives  restricted,  though  not  identical,  types.  An  example  in  point 
is  furnished  by  the  vertical  parabolas  tangent  to  a  fixed  line,  the 
equation  of  the  system  being  y  =  (ax+hy.  From  the  algebraic  or 
projective  point  of  view,  this  is  a  quadratic  system  since  the  para- 
meters are  involved  to  the  second  degree;  but  the  system  is  linear 
from  the  general  point  of  view  since  its  equation  may  be  written 
ax-\-h  —  \/y=0.  This  suggests  the  problem:  Determine  the  systems 
of  algebraic  curves  which  are  linear  in  the  general  sense. 

As  a  second  example,  consider,  from  both  points  of  view,  the 
equivalence  of  pencils  of  straight  lines  in  the  plane.  By  means  of 
collineations  any  two  pencils  may  be  converted  into  any  other  two; 

^  The  most  extensive  group  for  which  the  algebraic  configurations  form  a  body 
consists  of  all  algebraic  transformations.  It  is  rather  remarkable  that  even  this 
theory  has  received  no  development. 

*  Halphen,  Laguerre,  Forsj4;h.  This  theory  has  been  extended  to  simultaneous 
equations  and  applied  geometrically  by  E.  J.  Wilczynski  {Trans.  Amer.  Math. 
Soc,  1901-1904). 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY     581 

but  if  three  pencils  are  given,  it  is  necessary  to  distinguish  the  case 
where  the  three  base  points  are  in  a  straight  line  from  the  case  where 
they  are  not  so  situated.  We  thus  have  two  protectively  distinct 
cases,  which  may  be  represented  canonically  by:  (1)  a;=const., 
2/= const.,  x+ 2/= const.,  and  (2)  x= const.,  t/  =  const.,  y/z =const. 
The  first  type  may,  however,  be  converted  into  the  second  by  the 
transcendental  transformation  x^=^,y^=^,so  that,  in  the  general 
group  of  point  transformations,  all  sets  of  three  pencils  are  equivalent. 
The  discussion  for  four  or  more  pencils  yields  the  rather  surprising 
result  that  the  projective  classification  remains  valid  for  the  larger 
group. 

Dropping  these  special  considerations  on  algebraic  systems,  let  us 
pass  to  the  theory  of  arbitrary  systems  of  curves,  or,  what  is  equiva- 
lent, the  geometry  of  differential  equations.  While  belonging  to  the 
cycle  of  theories  due  primarily  to  Sophus  Lie,  it  has  received  little 
development  in  the  purely  geometric  direction.  Most  attention  has 
been  devoted  to  special  classes  of  differential  equations  with  respect 
to  special  groups  of  transformations.  Thus  there  is  an  extensive 
theory  of  the  homogeneous  linear  equations  with  respect  to  the 
group  x^=$(x),  yi=yTj(x)  which  leaves  the  entire  class  invariant.^ 
A  special  theosy  which  deserves  development  is  that  of  equations  of 
the  first  order  with  respect  to  the  infinite  group  of  conformal  trans- 
formations. 

As  regards  the  general  group  of  all  point  transformations,  all 
equations  of  the  first  order  are  equivalent,  so  that  the  first  case  of 
interest  is  the  theory  of  the  two-parameter  systems.  The  invariants 
of  the  differential  equation  of  second  order  have  been  discussed 
most  completely  in  the  prize  essay  of  A.  Tresse  (submitted  to  the 
Jablonowski  Gesellschaft  in  1896),  with  application  to  the  equiva- 
lence problem.  A  specially  important  class,  treated  earlier  by  Lie 
and  R.  Liouville,  consists  of  the  equations  of  cubic  type 

y''=Ay''+By''  +  Cy'+D, 
where  the  coefficients  are  functions  of  x,  y.  It  includes,  in  particular, 
the  general  linear  system  and  all  systems  capable  of  representing 
the  geodesies  of  any  surface.  While  the  analytical  conditions  which 
characterize  these  subclasses  are  known,  little  advance  has  been 
made  in  their  geometric  interpretation. 

Perhaps  the  simplest  configuration  belonging  to  the  field  considered, 
that  is,  having  properties  invariant  under  all  point  transformations, 
is  that  composed  of  three  simply  infinite  systems  of  curves,  which 
may  be  represented  analytically  by  an  equation  of  third  degree  in 
y'  with  one-valued  functions  of  x,  y  for  coefficients.  In  the  case  of 
equations  of  the  fourth  and  higher  degree  in  y' ,  certain  invariants 

^  The  elementary  (metric)  theory  of  curve  systems  has  been  too  much  neglected ; 
it  may  be  compared  in  interest  and  extent  with  the  usual  theory  of  surfaces. 


582  GEOMETRY 

may  be  found  immediately  from  the  fact  that  when  x  and  y  undergo 
an  arbitrary  transformation,  the  derivative  y'  undergoes  a  fractional 
linear  transformation  (of  special  type).  The  invariants  found  from 
this  algebraic  principle  are,  however,  in  a  sense,  trivial,  and  the  real 
problem  remains  almost  untouched:  to  determine  the  essential 
invariants  due  to  the  differential  relations  coimecting  the  coefficients 
in  the  linear  transformation  of  the  derivative. 

General  Theory  of  Transformations 

Closely  connected  with  the  geometry  of  differential  equations 
that  we  have  been  considering  is  the  geometry  of  point  transform- 
ations. In  the  former  theory  the  transformations  enter  only  as 
instruments,  in  the  latter  these  instruments  are  made  the  subject- 
matter  of  the  investigation.  The  distinction  is  parallel  to  that  which 
occurs  in  projective  geometry  between  the  theory  of  projective 
properties  of  curves  and  surfaces  and  the  properties  of  collineations. 
(It  may  be  remarked,  however,  that  although  a  transformation  is 
generally  regarded  as  dynamic  and  a  configuration  as  static,  the 
distinction  is  not  at  all  essential.  Thus  a  point  transformation  or 
correspondence  between  the  points  of  a  plane  may  be  viewed  as 
simply  a  double  infinity  of  point  pairs;  on  the  other  hand,  a  curve 
in  the  plane  may  be  regarded  as  the  equivalent  of  a  correspondence 
between  the  points  of  two  straight  lines. ^) 

We  consider  first  two  problems  concerning  the  general  (analytic) 
point  transformation  which  are  of  interest  and  importance  from  the 
theoretic  standpoint.  The  one  relates  to  the  discussion  of  the  char- 
acter of  such  a  transformation  in  the  neighborhood  of  a  given  point. 
Transon's  theorem  states  that  the  effect  of  any  analytic  transform- 
ation upon  an  infinitesimal  region  is  the  same  as  that  of  a  pro- 
jective transformation.  This  is  true,  however,  only  in  general;  it 
ceases  to  hold  when  the  derivatives  of  the  defining  functions  vanish 
at  the  point  considered.  What  is  the  character  of  the  transformation 
in  the  neighborhood  of  such  singular  points  ? 

A  more  fundamental  problem  relates  to  the  theory  of  equiva- 
lence. Consider  a  transformation  T  which  puts  in  correspondence 
the  points  P  and  Q  of  a  plane.  Let  the  entire  plane  be  subjected  to 
a  transformation  S  which  converts  P  into  P'  and  Q  into  Q\  We  thus 
obtain  a  new  transformation  T'  in  which  P'  and  Q'  are  corresponding 
points.  This  is  termed  the  transform  of  3"  by  means  of  /S,the  relation 
being  expressed  symbolically  by  T'  =S~'^TS.  The  question  then  arises 
whether  all  transformations  are  equivalent,  that  is,  can  any  one  be 
converted  into  any  other  in  the  manner  defined.  The  answer  de- 
pends on  certain  functional  equations  which  also  arise  in  connection 

^  Geometry  on  a  straight  line,  in  its  entirety,  is  as  rich  as  geometry  in  a  plane 
or  in  space  of  any  number  of  dimensions. 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      583 

with  the  question  whether  an  arbitrary  transformation  belongs  to 
a  continuous  group.  The  problem  deserves  treatment  not  merely  for 
the  analytic  transformations,  but  also  for  the  algebraic  and  for 
the  continuous  transformations.^ 

Aside  from  such  fundamental  questions,  further  development 
is  desirable  both  in  the  study  of  the  general  properties  (associated 
curve  systems  and  contact  relations)  of  an  arbitrary  transforma- 
tion, and  in  the  introduction  of  new  special  types  of  transformation, 
for  instance,  those  which  may  be  regarded  as  natural  extensions  of 
familiar  types. 

The  main  problems  in  the  theory  of  point  transformation  are 
connected  with  certain  fields  of  application  which  we  now  pass  in 
review. 

1.  Cartography.  A  map  may  be  regarded,  abstractly,  as  the  point 
by  point  representation  of  one  surface  upon  another,  the  case  of 
especial  practical  importance  being,  of  course,  the  representation  of 
a  spherical  or  spheroidal  surface  upon  the  plane.  As  it  is  impossible 
to  map  any  but  the  developable  surfaces  without  distortion  upon  a 
plane,  the  chief  types  of  available  representation  are  characterized 
by  the  invariance  of  certain  elements,  as  angles  or  areas,  or  the 
simple  depiction  of  certain  curves,  as  of  geodesies  by  straight  lines. 
Most  attention  has  been  devoted  to  the  conformal  type,  but  the 
question  proposed  by  Gauss  remains  unsolved:  what  is  the  best 
conformal  representation  of  a  given  surface  on  the  plane,  that  is, 
the  one  accompanied  by  the  minimum  distortion?  The  answer,  of 
course,  depends  on  the  criterion  adopted  for  measuring  the  degree 
of  distortion,  and  it  is  in  this  direction  that  progress  is  to  be 
expected. 

2.  Mathematical  theory  of  elasticity.  As  a  geometric  foundation 
for  the  mechanics  of  continua,  it  is  necessary  to  study  the  most 
general  deformation  of  space,  defined  say  by  putting  Xi,  yi,  Zi  equal 
to  arbitrary  functions  of  x,  y,  z.  The  most  elegant  analytical  repre- 
sentation, as  given  for  instance  in  the  memoir  of  E.  and  F.  Cosserat 
(Annales  de  Toulouse,  volume  10),  is  obtained  by  introducing  the 
elements  of  length  ds  and  ds^  before  and  after  deformation,  and  the 
related  quadratic  diifferential  form  dsf  —  ds^=2e^dx^+2e^dy^+2e3dz^ 
+2y^  dydz-\-2y^  dxdz+2y^dxdy.  The  theory  is  thus  seen  to  be  ana- 
logous to  though  of  course  more  complicated  than  the  usual  theory  of 
surfaces.  The  six  functions  of  x,  y,  z  which  appear  as  coefficients 
in  this  form  are  termed  the  components  of  the  deformation.    Their 

'  This  problem  is  not  to  be  confused  with  the  similar  (but  simpler)  question 
connected  with  Lie's  division  of  (analytic)  groups  into  demokratisch  and  aristo- 
kratisch.  In  those  of  the  first  kind  all  the  infinitesimal  transformations  are 
equivalent,  in  those  of  the  second  there  exist  non-equivalent  infinitesimal  trans- 
formations. Lie  shows  that  all  finite  groups  are  aristokratisch,  while  the  groups 
of  all  (analytic)  point  and  contact  transformations  are  demokratisch.  Cf.  Leip- 
ziger  Berichte,  vol.  xlvii  (1895),  p.  271. 


584  GEOMETRY 

importance  is  due  to  the  fact  that  they  vanish  only  when  the  trans- 
formation is  a  rigid  displacement,  so  that  two  deformations  have 
the  same  components  when,  and  only  when,  they  differ  by  a  dis- 
placement. The  case  where  the  components  are  constants  leads  to 
the  homogeneous  deformation  (or  afiine  transformation  of  the  geo- 
meters), the  type  considered  almost  exclusively  in  the  usual  dis- 
cussions of  elasticity.  It  would  seem  desirable  to  study  in  detail 
the  next  case  which  presents  itself,  namely,  that  in  which  the  com- 
ponents are  linear  functions  of  x,  y,  z. 

In  the  general  deformation,  the  six  components  are  not  inde- 
pendent, but  are  connected  by  nine  differential  equations  analogous 
to  those  of  Codazzi.  The  fact  that  a  transformation  is  defined  by 
three  independent  functions  indicates,  however,  that  there  should  be 
only  three  distinct  relations  between  the  components.  This  means 
that  the  nine  equations  of  condition  which  occur  in  the  standard 
theory  are  themselves  interdependent;  but  their  relations  (analogous 
to  syzygies  among  syzygies  in  the  algebra  of  forms)  do  not  appear 
to  have  been  worked  out. 

3.  Vector  -fields.  From  its  beginning  in  the  Faraday-Maxwell 
theory  of  electricity  until  the  present  day,  the  course  which  the 
discussion  of  vector  fields  has  followed  has  been  guided  almost 
entirely  by  external  considerations,  namely,  the  physical  applications. 
While  this  is  advantageous  in  many  respects,  it  cannot  be  denied 
that  it  has  led  to  lack  of  symmetry  and  generality.  The  time  seems 
to  be  ripe  for  a  more  systematic  mathematical  development.  The 
vector  field  deserves  to  be  introduced  as  a  standard  form  into  geo- 
metry. 

Abstractly,  such  a  field  is  equivalent  to  a  point  transformation  of 
space,  since  each  is  represented  by  three  scalar  relations  in  six  variables. 
Instead  of  taking  these  variables  as  the  coordinates  of  corresponding 
points,  it  is  more  convenient  to  consider  three  as  the  coordinates 
X,  y,  z  oi  a.  particle  and  t'he  other  three  as  components  u,  v,  w  of  its 
velocity;  we  thus  picture  the  set  of  functional  relations  by  means 
of  the  steady  motion  of  a  hypothetical  space-filling  fluid.  This  image 
should  be  of  service  even  in  abstract  analysis ;  for  its  role  is  analogous 
to  that  of  the  curve  in  dealing  with  a  single  relation  between  two 
variables.  The  streaming  of  a  material  fluid  is,  of  course,  not  suffi- 
ciently general  for  such  a  purpose,  since,  in  virtue  of  the  equation  of 
continuity,  it  images  only  a  particular  class  of  vector  fields. 

In  addition  to  the  ordinary  vector  fields,  physics  makes  use  of 
so-called  hypervector  fields,  which,  geometrically,  lead  to  configur- 
ations consisting  of  a  triply  infinite  system  of  quadric  surfaces,  one 
for  each  point  of  space.  In  the  special  case  of  interest  in  hydro- 
dynamics (irrotational  motion),  the  configuration  simplifies  in  that 
the  quadrics  are  ellipsoids  about  the  corresponding  points  as  centres. 


PRESENT  PROBLEMS  OF  GEOMETRY      585 

This  is  equivalent  to  the  tensor  field  which  arises  in  studying  the 
moments  of  inertia  of  an  arbitrary  distribution  of  mass.  The  more 
general  case  actually  arises  in  Maxwell's  theory  of  magnetism. 

4.  As  a  final  domain  of  application  we  mention  the  class  of  ques- 
tions which  have  received  systematic  treatment,  under  the  title  of 
nomography,  only  during  the  past  few  years.  This  subject  deals  with 
the  methods  of  representing  graphically,  in  a  plane,  functional 
relations  containing  any  number  of  variables.  Thus  a  function  of 
two  independent  variables,  z=f{x,  y),  may  be  represented  by  the 
system  of  plane  curves  f(x,  y)  =  c,  each  marked  with  the  correspond- 
ing value  of  the  parameter.  This  "  parametered "  system  is  then 
a  cartesian  graphical  table,  which  is  the  simplest  type  of  abacus  or 
nomogram. 

By  means  of  any  point  transformation,  one  nomogram  is  con- 
verted into  another  which  may  serve  to  represent  the  same  functional 
relation.  The  importance  of  this  process  of  conversion  (the  so-called 
anamorphosis  of  Lalanne  and  Massau)  depends  on  the  fact  that  it 
may  replace  a  complicated  table  by  a  simpler.  The  problems  which 
arise  (for  example,  the  determination  of  aU  relations  between  three 
variables  which  can  be  represented  by  a  nomogram  composed  of 
three  systems  of  straight  lines^)  are  of  both  practical  and  theoretical 
interest.  The  literature  is  scattered  through  the  French,  ItaUan, 
and  German  technological  journals,  but  a  systematic  presentation 
of  the  main  results  is  to  be  found  in  the  Traite  de  Nomographie 
of  d'Ocagne  (Paris,  1899). 

We  return  to  the  abstract  theory  of  transformations.  The  type 
of  transformation  we  have  been  considering,  converting  point  into 
point,  is  only  a  special  case  of  more  general  types.  The  most  im- 
portant extension  hitherto  made  depends  upon  the  introduction  of 
differential  elements.  Thus  the  lineal  element  or  directed  point 
(x,  y,  y')  leads  to  transformations  which  in  general  convert  a  point 
into  a  system  of  elements;  when  the  latter  form  a  curve,  every  curve 
is  converted  into  a  curve  and  the  result  is  termed  a  contact  trans- 
formation. Backlund  has  shown  that  no  extension  results  from  the 
elements  of  second  or  higher  order:  osculation  transformations  are 
necessarily  contact  transformations.  The  discussion  of  elements  of 
infinitely  high  order,  defined  by  an  infinite  set  of  coordinates  {x,  y, 
y'  1  y" ,  •  •  •);  i^is-y  perhaps  lead  to  a  real  extension.  The  question  may 
be  put  in  this  form:  Are  there  transformations  (in  addition  to  or- 
dinary contact  transformations)  which  convert  analytic  curves  into 
analytic  curves  in  such  a  way  that  contact  is  an  invariant  relation? 
The  idea  of  curve  transformation  in  general  will  probably  be  worked 

^  The  case  of  three  systems  of  circles  has  also  been  discussed.  See  d'Ocagne, 
Journal  de  I'Ecole  Polytechnique,  1902. 


586  GEOMETRY 

out  in  the  near  future :  what  is  the  most  general  mode  of  setting  up 
a  correspondence  which  associates  with  every  Jordan  curve  another 
Jordan  curve?  Such  discussions  are  aspects  of  geometry  with  an 
infinite  number  of  dimensions. 

After  a  review  of  the  kind  given  in  this  paper,  one  is  tempted  to 
ask:  What  is  it  which  influences  the  mathematician  in  selecting 
certain  (out  of  an  infinite  number  of  equally  conceivable)  problems 
for  investigations?  It  is  true,  of  course,  that  his  subject  is  ideal, 
self-created,  and  that  "Das  Wesen  der  Mathematik  liegt  in  ihrer 
Freiheit."  Georg  Cantor  would  indeed  replace  the  term  pure  mathe- 
matics by  free  mathematics.  This  freedom,  however,  is  not  entirely 
caprice.  The  investigators  of  each  age  have  always  felt  it  their 
duty  to  deal  with  the  unsolved  questions  and  to  generalize  the  re- 
sults and  conceptions  inherited  from  the  past,  to  correlate  with 
other  fields  of  contemporaneous  thought,  to  keep  in  contact,  as  far 
as  possible,  with  the  whole  body  of  truth.  This  is  not  all,  however. 
The  influence  of  aesthetic  considerations,  though  less  subject  to 
analysis,  has  been,  and  still  is,  of  at  least  equal  importance  in  guiding 
the  course  of  mathematical  development. 


SHORT   PAPERS 

The  Section  of  Geometry  was  very  fully  attended  and  productive  of  extended 
discussion  and  a  number  of  supplementary  papers.  For  the  same  reason  as  in  the 
Section  of  Algebra  and  Analysis  it  is  impossible  to  give  a  satisfactory  resume  of 
the  short  papers  on  this  subject  owing  to  their  close  technical  reasoning. 

The  first  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  Harris  Hancock,  of  the  University 
of  Cincinnati,  on  "Algebraic  Minimal  Surfaces." 

The  second  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  H.  T.  Bhchfeldt,  of  Leland  Stan- 
ford Jr.  University,  on  the  subject  "Concerning  some  Geometrical  Properties 
of  Surfaces  of  Revolution." 

The  third  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  George  Bruce  Halsted,  of  Kenyon 
College,  on  "  Non-Euclidean  Spherics." 

The  fourth  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  Arnold  Emch,  of  the  University 
of  Colorado,  on  "The  Configuration  of  the  Points  of  Inflection  of  a  Plane 
Cubic  and  their  Harmonic  Polars." 

The  fifth  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  H.  P.  Manning,  of  Brown  University, 
on  "  Representation  of  Complex  Variables  in  Space  of  Four  Dimensions." 

The  sixth  paper  was  read  by  Professor  G.  A.  Bliss,  of  the  University  of  Missouri, 
on  "Concerning  Calcidus  of  Variations." 

The  seventh  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  L.  W.  Dowling,  of  the  University 
of  Wisconsin,  on  "Certain  Universal  Curves." 


SECTION  C— APPLIED  MATHEMATICS 


SECTION  C— APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 


{Hall  7,  September  24,  3  p.  m.) 

Chairman  :     Professor  Arthur  G.  Webster,  Clark  University,    Worcester, 
Mass. 

Speakers:     Professor  Ludwig  Boltzmann,  University  of  Vienna. 

Professor  Henri  Poincare,  The  Sorbonne;  Member  of  the  Insti- 
tute of  France. 

Secretary:  Professor  Henry  T.  Eddy,  University  of  Minnesota. 


THE  RELATIONS  OF  APPLIED  MATHEMATICS 

BY    LUDWIG    BOLTZMANN 
{Translated  from  the  German  by  Professor  S.  Epsteen,  University  of  Chicago) 

[Ludwig  Boltzmann,  Professor  of  Physics,  University  of  Vienna,  since  1902. 
b.  Vienna,  Austria,  1840.  Studied,  Vienna,  Heidelberg,  and  Berlin.  Professor 
of  Physico-Mathematics,  University  of  Gratz,  1869-73;  Professor  of  Mathe- 
matics, University  of  Vienna,  1873-76;  Professor  of  Experimental  Physics, 
University  of  Gratz,  1876-90;  Professor  of  Theoretical  Physics,  University 
of  Munich,  1891-95;  ibid.  University  of  Vienna,  1895-1900;  Professor  of 
Physics,  University  of  Leipzig,  1900-02.  Author  of  Vorlesungen  iiber  Max- 
well's Theorie  der  Elekt  rizitat  und  des  Lichts;  Vorlesungen  iiber  Kinetische 
Gastheorie;   Vorlesungen  iiber  die  Prinzipe  der  Mechanik.] 

My  present  lecture  has  been  put  under  the  heading  of  applied 
mathematics,  while  my  activity  as  a  teacher  and  investigator  be- 
longs to  the  science  of  physics.  The  immense  gap  which  divides 
the  latter  science  into  two  distinct  camps  has  almost  nowhere  been 
so  sharply  emphasized  as  in  the  division  of  the  lecture  material 
of  this  scientific  congress,  which  covers  such  an  enormous  range  of 
subjects  that  one  may  designate  it  as  a  flood,  or,  to  preserve  local 
coloring,  as  a  Niagara  of  scientific  lectures.  I  speak  of  the  division 
of  physics  into  theoretical  and  experimental.  Although  I  have 
been  assigned,  as  representative  of  theoretical  physics,  to  "A. — 
Normative  Science,"  experimental  physics  appears  much  later  under 
'' C. — Physical  Science."  Between  them  lie  history,  science  of  lan- 
guage, literature,  art,  and  science  of  religion.  Over  all  this,  however, 
the  theoretical  physicist  must  extend  his  hand  to  the  experimental 
physicist.  We  shall  therefore  not  be  able  to  avoid  entirely  the  ques- 
tion of  the  justification  of  dividing  physics  into  two  parts  and,  in 
particular,  into  theoretical  and  experimental. 

Let  us  listen  first  of  all  to  an  investigator  of  a  time  when  natural 
science  had  not  yet  grown  beyond  its  first  beginnings,  to  Emmanuel 
Kant.    Kant  requires  of  each  science  that  it  should  be  developed 


592  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

logically  from  unified  principles  and  firmly  established  theories. 
Natural  science  seems  to  him  a  primary  science  only  in  so  far  as 
it  rests  on  a  mathematical  basis.  Thus,  he  does  not  reckon  the  chem- 
istry of  his  day  among  the  sciences,  because  it  rests  merely  upon 
an  empirical  basis  and  lacks  a  unified,  regulative  principle. 

From  this  point  of  view  theoretical  physics  is  preferred  to  ex- 
perimental physics,  and  occupies,  in  a  sense,  a  higher  rank.  Experi- 
mental physics  was  merely  to  gather  the  material,  but  it  remained 
for  the  theoretical  physics  to  form  the  structure. 

But  the  succession  in  the  order  of  rank  becomes  reversed  when 
we  take  into  account  the  acquisitions  of  the  last  decades  as  well  as 
the  progress  which  is  to  be  expected  in  the  immediate  future.  The 
chain  of  experimental  discoveries  of  the  last  century  received  a 
fitting  completion  with  the  discovery  of  the  Rontgen  rays.  Con- 
nected with  these  there  appear  in  the  present  century  a  multitude 
of  new  rays,  with  the  most  enigmatical  properties,  which  have  the 
profoundest  effects  upon  our  conceptions  of  nature.  The  more 
enigmatical  these  newly  discovered  facts  are,  and  the  more  they 
seem  at  first  to  contradict  our  present  conceptions,  the  greater  the 
successes  which  they  promise  for  the  future.  But  this  is  not  the  occa- 
sion for  the  discussion  of  these  experimental  triumphs.  I  must  leave 
to  the  representatives  of  experimental  physics  at  this  Congress  the 
prolific  problem  of  portraying  all  of  the  fruits  which  have  hitherto 
been  gathered  in  this  domain,  one  might  almost  say,  daily,  and 
those  which  are  to  be  expected. 

The  representative  of  theoretical  physics  scarcely  finds  himself  in 
an  equally  fortunate  position.  Great  activity  does  indeed  prevail 
in  this  domain.  One  could  almost  say  that  it  is  in  process  of  revolu- 
tion. Only  how  much  less  tangible  are  the  results  here  attained  in 
comparison  with  those  in  experimental  physics!  It  appears  here 
that  in  a  certain  sense  experimentation  deserves  precedence  over 
all  theory.  An  immediate  fact  is  at  once  comprehensible.  Its  fruits 
may  become  evident  in  the  shortest  time,  such  as  the  various  appli- 
cations of  the  Rontgen  rays  and  the  utilization  of  the  Hertz  waves 
in  wireless  telegraphy.  The  battle  which  the  theories  have  to  fight 
is,  however,  an  infinitely  wearisome  one;  indeed,  it  seems  as  if  cer- 
tain disputed  questions  which  existed  from  the  beginning  wiU  live 
as  long  as  the  science. 

Every  firmly  established  fact  remains  forever  unchangeable;  at 
most,  it  may  be  generalized,  completed,  additions  may  be  made, 
but  it  cannot  be  completely  upset.  Thus  it  is  explained  why  the 
development  of  experimental  physics  is  continuously  progressive, 
never  making  a  sudden  jump,  and  never  visited  by  great  tremblings 
and  revolutions.  It  occurs  only  in  rare  instances  that  something 
which  was  regarded  as  a  fact  turns  out  afterwards  to  have  been  an 


RELATIONS   OF   APPLIED   MATHEMATICS         593 

error,  and  in  such  cases  the  explanations  of  the  errors  follow  soon, 
and  they  are  not  of  great  influence  on  the  structure  of  the  science  as 
a  whole. 

It  is,  indeed,  strongly  emphasized  that  every  established  and 
logically  recognized  truth  must  remain  incontrovertible.  Although 
this  cannot  be  doubted,  experience  teaches  that  the  structure  of  our 
theories  is  by  no  means  composed  entirely  of  such  incontrovertibly 
established  truths.  They  are  composed  rather  of  many  arbitrary 
pictures  of  the  connections  between  phenomena,  of  so-called  hypo- 
theses. 

Without  some  departure,  however  slight,  from  direct  observation, 
a  theory  or  even  an  intelligibly  connected  practical  description  for 
predicting  the  facts  of  nature  cannot  exist.  This  is  equally  true  of 
the  old  theories  whose  foundations  have  become  questionable,  and 
of  the  most  modern  ones,  which  are  resigning  themselves  to  a  great 
illusion  if  they  regard  themselves  as  free  from  hypotheses. 

The  hypotheses  may  perhaps  be  indefinite,  or  may  be  in  the  shape 
of  mathematical  formulae,  or  the  thought  may  be  equivalent  to  the 
latter,  but  expressed  in  words.  In  the  latter  cases  the  agreement 
with  given  data  may  be  checked  step  by  step;  a  complete  revolu- 
tion of  that  previously  constructed  is  indeed  not  absolutely  impos- 
sible, as,  for  example,  if  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  energy  should 
turn  out  to  be  incorrect.  But  such  a  revolution  will  be  exceedingly 
rare  and  highly  improbable. 

Such  an  indefinite,  slightly  specialized  theory  might  serve  as  a 
guiding  thread  for  experiments  whose  purpose  is  a  detailed  develop- 
ment of  knowledge  previously  acquired  and  which  is  proceeding  in 
barren  channels ;  beyond  this  its  usefulness  does  not  reach. 

In  contradistinction  to  these  are  the  hypotheses  which  give  the 
imagination  room  for  play  and  by  boldly  going  beyond  the  material 
at  hand  afford  continual  inspiration  for  new  experiments,  and  are 
thus  pathfinders  for  the  most  unexpected  discoveries.  Such  a  theory 
will  indeed  be  subject  to  change,  a  very  complicated  mass  of  inform- 
ation will  be  brought  together  and  will  then  be  replaced  by  a  new 
and  more  comprehensive  theory  in  which  the  old  one  will  be  the  pic- 
ture of  a  limited  type  of  phenomena.  Examples  of  this  are  the  theory 
of  emission  in  regard  to  the  description  of  the  phenomena  of  catoptrics 
and  dioptrics,  the  hypothesis  of  an  elastic  ether  in  the  representation 
of  the  phenomena  of  interference  and  refraction  of  light,  and  the 
notion  of  the  electric  fluid  in  the  description  of  the  phenomena  of 
electrostatics. 

Moreover  the  theories  which  proudly  designate  themselves  as  free 
from  hypotheses  are  not  exempt  from  great  revolutions;  thus,  no  one 
will  doubt  that  the  so-called  theory  of  energy  will  have  completely 
to  alter  its  form  if  it  desires  to  remain  effective. 


594  APPLIED    MATHEMATICS 

The  accusation  has  been  made  that  physical  hypotheses  have 
sometimes  proved  injurious  and  have  delayed  the  progress  of  the 
science.  This  accusation  is  based  chiefly  upon  the  role  which  the 
hypothesis  of  the  electric  fluid  has  played  in  the  development  of  the 
theory  of  electricity.  This  hypothesis  was  brought  to  a  high  stage 
of  perfection  by  Wilhelm  Weber,  and  the  general  recognition  which 
his  works  found  in  Germany  did  indeed  stand  in  the  road  of  the 
theory  of  Maxwell.  In  a  similar  manner  Newton's  emanation  theory 
stood  in  the  way  of  the  theory  of  undulations.  But  such  incon- 
veniences can  scarcely  be  entirely  avoided  in  the  future.  It  will  al- 
ways be  the  tendency  to  complete  as  far  as  possible  the  prevailing 
view,  and  to  make  it  self-sufficient  whenever  such  a  theory  is  self- 
consistent  and  does  not  in  any  way  lead  to  a  contradiction,  whether 
it  consist  of  mechanical  models,  of  geometrical  pictures,  or  of  mathe- 
matical formulas.  It  will  always  be  possible  that  a  new  theory  will 
arise  which  has  not  yet  been  tested  by  experiment  and  which  will 
represent  a  much  larger  field  of  phenomena.  In  such  cases  the  older 
theory  will  count  the  largest  following  until  this  field  of  phenomena 
is  brought  into  the  range  of  experiment,  and  decisive  tests  demon- 
strate the  superiority  of  the  newer  one.  It  is  certainly  useful,  if  the 
theory  of  Weber  be  always  held  up  as  a  warning  example,  that  one 
should  bear  in  mind  the  essential  progressiveness  of  the  intellect. 
The  services  of  Weber  are  not  decreased  by  this,  however;  Maxwell 
himself  speaks  of  his  theory  with  the  greatest  wonder.  Indeed,  this 
instance  cannot  be  taken  into  consideration  against  the  usefulness  of 
hypotheses,  since  Maxwell's  theory  contained  as  much  of  the  hypo- 
thetical as  any  other.  And  this  was  eliminated  only  after  it  became 
generally  known  through  Hertz,  Poynting,  and  others. 

The  accusation  has  also  been  raised  against  hypotheses  in  physics 
that  the  creation  and  development '  of  mathematical  methods  for 
the  computation  of  the  hypothetical  molecular  motions  has  been 
useless  and  even  harmful.  This  accusation  I  cannot  recognize  as 
substantiated.  Were  it  so,  the  theme  selected  for  my  present  lecture 
would  be  an  unfortunate  one;  and  this  fact  may  excuse  me  for 
having  lingered  on  this  much-discussed  subject  and  for  having  sought 
to  justify  the  use  of  hypotheses  in  physics. 

I  have  not  chosen  for  the  thesis  of  my  present  lecture  the  entire 
development  of  physical  theory.  Several  years  ago  I  treated  this 
subject  at  the  German  Naturforscherversammlung  in  Munich,  and 
although  some  new  developments  have  taken  place  since  then,  I 
should  have  to  repeat  myself  a  great  deal.  Moreover,  one  who  has 
committed  himself  to  one  faction  is  not  in  a  position  to  judge  the 
other  factions  in  a  completely  objective  manner.  I  do  not  refer  to  a 
criticism  of  its  value;  my  lecture  shall  not  criticise,  but  shall  judge. 
I  am  also  convinced  of  the  value  of  the  views  of  my  opponents  and 


RELATIONS   OF  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS         595 

only  arise  to  repel  them  when  they  attempt  to  belittle  mine.  But 
one  can  scarcely  give  as  complete  an  account  according  to  subject- 
matter,  and  an  exposition  of  the  inter-relations  of  all  ideas  in  the 
views  of  another,  as  in  his  own, 

I  shall  therefore  select  as  the  goal  of  my  lecture  to-day  not  merely 
the  kinetic  theory  of  molecules,  but,  moreover,  a  highly  specialized 
branch  of  it.  Far  from  denying  that  it  contains  hypotheses,  I  must 
rather  characterize  it  as  a  bold  advance  beyond  the  facts  of  observa- 
tion. And  I  nevertheless  do  not  consider  it  unworthy  of  this  occa- 
sion; this  much  faith  do  I  have  in  hypotheses  which  present  certain 
peculiarities  of  observation  in  a  new  light  or  which  bring  forth  rela- 
tions among  them  which  cannot  be  reached  by  other  methods.  We 
must  indeed  be  mindful  of  the  fact  that  hypotheses  require  and  are 
capable  of  continuous  development,  and  are  only  then  to  be  aban- 
doned when  all  the  relations  which  they  represent  can  be  better 
understood  in  some  other  manner. 

To  the  above-mentioned  problems,  which  are  as  old  as  the  science 
and  still  unsolved,  belongs  the  one  if  matter  is  continuous,  or  if  it 
is  to  be  considered  as  made  up  of  discrete  parts,  of  very  many,  but 
not  in  the  mathematical  sense  infinite,  individuals.  This  is  one  of 
the  difficult  questions  which  form  the  boundary  of  philosophy  and 
physics. 

Even  some  decades  ago,  scientists  felt  very  shy  of  going  deeply 
into  the  discussion  of  such  questions.  The  one  before  us  is  too  real 
to  be  entirely  avoided;  but  one  cannot  discuss  it  without  touching  on 
some  profounder  still,  such  as  upon  the  nature  of  the  law  of  causation, 
of  matter,  of  force,  and  so  forth.  The  latter  are  the  ones  of  which  it 
was  said  that  they  did  not  trouble  the  scientist,  that  they  belonged 
entirely  to  philosophy.  To-day  the  situation  is  different,  there  is 
evident  a  tendency  among  scientists  to  consider  philosophic  questions, 
and  properly  so.  One  of  the  first  rules  of  science  is  never  to  trust 
blindly  to  the  instrument  with  which  one  works,  but  to  test  it  in 
all  directions.  How,  then,  are  we  to  trust  blindly  to  inherited  and 
historically  developed  conceptions,  particularly  when  there  are 
instances  known  where  they  led  us  into  error  ?  But  in  the  examina- 
tion of  even  the  simplest  elements,  where  is  the  boundary  between 
science  and  philosophy  at  which  we  should  pause  ? 

I  hope  that  none  of  the  philosophers  present  will  take  offense  or 
perceive  an  accusation,  if  I  say  boldly  that  by  assigning  this  question 
to  philosophy  the  resulting  success  has  been  rather  meagre.  Philo- 
sophy has  done  noticeably  little  toward  the  explanation  of  these 
questions,  and  from  her  own  one-sided  point  of  view  she  can  do  so  just 
as  little  as  natural  science  can  from  hers.  If  real  progress  is  possible, 
it  is  only  to  be  expected  by  cooperation  of  both  of  these  sciences. 
May  I  therefore  be  pardoned  if  I  touch  slightly  upon  these  questions 


596  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

although  not  a  specialist;  their  connection  with  the  aim  of  my  lec- 
ture is  very  intimate. 

Let  us  consult  the  famous  thinker  already  quoted,  Emmanuel 
Kant,  on  the  question  if  matter  is  continuous,  or  if  it  is  composed 
of  atoms.  He  treats  of  this  in  his  Antimonies.  Of  all  the  questions 
there  raised,  he  shows  that  both  the  pro  and  con  can  be  logically 
demonstrated.  It  can  be  shown  rigorously  that  there  is  no  limit  to 
the  divisibility  of  matter  while  an  infinite  divisibility  contradicts  the 
laws  of  logic.  Kant  shows  likewise  that  a  beginning  and  end  of  time, 
a  boundary  where  space  ceases,  are  as  inconceivable  as  absolutely 
endless  duration,  absolutely  endless  extension. 

This  is  by  no  means  the  sole  instance  where  philosophical  thought 
becomes  tangled  in  contradictions;  indeed,  one  finds  them  at  every 
step.  The  ordinary  things  of  philosophy  are  sources  of  insolvable 
riddles;  to  explain  our  perceptions  it  invents  the  concept  of  matter 
and  then  finds  that  it  is  altogether  unsuited  to  possess  perception 
itself  or  to  generate  perception  in  a  spirit.  With  consummate  acumen 
it  constructs  the  concept  of  space,  or  of  time,  and  finds  that  it  is 
absolutely  impossible  that  things  should  exist  in  this  space,  that 
events  should  occur  during  this  time.  It  finds  insurmountable 
difficulties  in  the  relation  of  cause  to  effect,  of  body  and  soul,  in 
the  possibility  of  consciousness,  in  short,  everywhere  and  in  every- 
thing. Indeed,  it  finally  finds  it  inexplicable  and  self-contradictory 
that  anything  can  exist  at  all,  that  something  originated  and  is  cap- 
able of  continuing,  that  everything  can  be  classified  according  to 
our  categories,  nor  that  there  is  a  quite  perfect  classification.  Such 
a  classification  will  always  be  a  variable  one  and  adapted  to  the 
requirements  of  the  moment.  Also  the  breaking  up  of  physics  into 
theoretical  and  experimental  is  merely  a  consequence  of  the  preval- 
ent division  of  methods  and  will  not  last  forever. 

My  present  thesis  is  quite  different  from  the  one  that  certain 
questions  are  beyond  the  boundary  of  human  comprehension.  For 
according  to  the  latter,  there  is  a  deficiency,  an  incompleteness  in  the 
human  intelligence,  while  I  consider  the  existence  of  these  questions, 
these  problems,  as  an  illusion.  By  superficial  consideration  it  seems 
astonishing,  after  this  illusion  is  recognized,  that  the  impulse  to 
answer  those  questions  does  not  cease.  Habit  of  thought  is  much  too 
powerful  to  release  us. 

It  is  here  as  with  the  ordinary  illusion  which  continues  operative 
after  its  cause  is  recognized.  In  consequence  of  this  is  the  feeling  of 
uncertainty,  of  want  of  satisfaction  which  the  scientist  feels  when  he 
philosophizes.  These  illusions  will  yield  but  very  slowly  and  gradually, 
and  I  consider  it  as  one  of  the  chief  problems  of  philosophy  to  set 
forth  clearly  the  uselessness  of  reaching  beyond  the  limits  of  our 
habits  of  thought  and  to  strive,  in  the  choice  and  combination  of 


RELATIONS   OF   APPLIED  MATHEMATICS  597 

concepts  and  words,  to  give  the  most  useful  expression  of  facts  in  a 
manner  which  is  independent  of  our  inherited  habits.  Then  all  these 
complications  and  contradictions  must  vanish.  It  must  be  made 
clear  what  is  stone  in  the  structure  of  our  thoughts  and  what  is 
mortar,  and  the  oppressive  sentiment,  that  the  simplest  things  are 
the  most  inexpUcable  and  the  most  trivial  are  the  most  mysterious, 
becomes  mere  imagination-change. 

To  call  upon  logic  seems  to  me  as  if  one  were  to  put  on  for  a  trip 
into  the  mountains  a  long  flowing  robe,  which  always  wrapped 
itself  about  the  feet  so  that  one  fell  at  the  first  steps  while  on  the  level. 
The  source  of  this  kind  of  logic  is  the  immoderate  trust  in  the  so- 
called  laws  of  thought.  It  is  certain  that  we  could  not  gather  experi- 
ence did  we  not  have  certain  forms  of  connecting  phenomena,  that  is 
to  say,  of  thought,  innate.  If  we  wish  to  call  these  laws  of  thought, 
they  are  indeed  a  priori  to  the  extent  that  they  accompany  every 
experience  in  our  soul,  or  if  we  prefer,  in  our  brain.  Only  nothing 
seems  to  me  less  reasonable  than  the  conclusion  from  the  reasoning 
in  this  sense  to  certainty,  to  infallibility.  These  laws  of  thought 
have  been  developed  according  to  the  same  laws  of  evolution  as 
the  optical  apparatus  of  the  eye,  the  acoustic  apparatus  of  the  ear, 
and  the  pumping  arrangements  of  the  heart.  In  the  course  of  human 
development  everything  useless  was  eliminated,  and  thus  a  unity 
and  finish  arose  which  might  be  mistaken  for  infallibility.  Thus  the 
perfection  of  the  eye,  of  the  ear,  of  the  arrangement  of  the  heart 
excite  our  admiration,  without  the  absolute  perfection  of  these 
organs  being  emphasized,  however.  Just  so  little  should  the  laws  of 
thought  be  regarded  as  absolutely  infallible.  They  are  the  very  ones 
which  have  developed  with  regard  to  seizing  that  which  is  most 
necessary  and  practically  useful  in  the  maintenance  of  life.  With 
these,  the  results  of  experimental  investigation  show  more  relation 
than  the  examination  of  the  mechanism  of  thought.  We  should, 
therefore,  not  be  surprised  that  the  customary  forms  of  thought 
for  the  abstract  are  not  entirely  suited  to  practical  applications 
in  far  removed  problems  of  philosophy,  and  that  they  have  not 
become  applicable  since  the  days  of  Thales.  Therefore  the  simplest 
things  seem  to  be  the  most  puzzling  to  the  philosopher.  And  he 
finds  everywhere  contradictions;  these  are  nothing  more,  however, 
than  useless,  incorrect  facsimiles  of  that  which  is  given  us  through 
our  thoughts.  In  facts  there  can  be  no  contradictions.  As  soon  as 
contradictions  seem  unavoidable  we  must  test,  extend,  and  seek 
to  modify  that  which  we  call  laws  of  thought,  but  which  are  only 
inherited,  customary  representations,  preserved  for  aeons,  for  the 
description  of  practical  needs.  Just  as  to  the  inherited  discoveries 
of  the  cylinder,  the  carriage,  the  plow,  numerous  artificial  ones  have 
been  consciously  added,  so  must  we  improve,  artificially  and  con- 


598  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

sciously,  our  likewise  inherited  concepts.  Our  problem  cannot  be 
to  quote  facts  before  the  judgment  seat  of  our  laws  of  thought,  but 
to  fit  our  mental  representations  and  concepts  to  the  facts.  Since 
we  attempt  to  express  with  clearness  such  complicated  processes 
merely  by  words,  written,  spoken,  or  inwardly  thought,  it  might 
also  be  said  that  we  should  combine  the  words  in  such  wise  as  to 
give  the  most  appropriate  expression  of  the  facts,  that  the  relations 
indicated  by  our  words  should  be  most  adequate  for  the  relations 
among  the  actualities.  When  the  problem  is  enunciated  in  this 
fashion,  its  appropriate  solution  may  still  offer  the  greatest  difficulties, 
but  one  knows  then  the  end  in  view  and  will  not  stumble  on  self- 
made  difficulties. 

Much  that  is  useless  in  the  usage  and  in  the  bearing  of  the  nature 
of  life  is  brought  forth  by  a  method  of  treatment  which,  being 
useful  in  most  cases,  becomes  through  habit  a  second  nature,  until 
one  cannot  set  it  aside  when  it  becomes  inapplicable  somewhere. 
I  say  that  the  adaptability  goes  beyond  the  point  aimed  at.  This 
happens  frequently  in  the  commonplaces  of  thought,  and  becomes 
the  source  of  apparent  contradictions  between  the  laws  of  thought 
and  the  world,  as  well  as  between  the  laws  of  thought  themselves. 

Thus,  the  regularity  of  the  phenomena  of  nature  is  the  funda- 
mental condition  for  all  cognition;  thus  comes  the  habit  of  inquiring 
of  everything  the  cause,  the  non-resisting  compulsion,  and  we 
inquire  also  concerning  the  cause,  why  everything  must  have  a  cause. 
In  fact  people  strove  for  a  long  time  to  determine  if  cause  and  effect 
is  a  necessary  bond  or  merely  an  accidental  sequence,  and  if  it  did 
or  did  not  have  a  unique  meaning  to  say  that  a  certain  particular 
phenomenon  was  connected  with,  and  a  necessary  consequence  of, 
a  definite  group  of  other  phenomena. 

Similarly,  something  is  said  to  be  useful,  valuable,  if  it  satisfies  the 
needs  of  the  individual  or  of  humanity;  but  we  go  beyond  the  mark 
if  we  ask  concerning  the  value  of  life  itself,  if  such  it  seem  to  have, 
because  it  has  no  purpose  outside  of  itself.  The  same  happens  when 
we  strive  vainly  to  explain  the  simplest  concepts,  out  of  which  all 
others  are  built,  by  means  of  simpler  ones  still,  to  explain  the  simplest 
fundamental  laws. 

We  should  not  attempt  to  deduce  nature  from  our  concepts,  but 
should  adapt  the  latter  to  the  former.  We  should  not  believe  our 
inherited  rules  of  thought  to  be  conditions  preceding  our  more  com- 
plicated experiences,  for  they  are  not  so  for  the  simplest  essentials. 
They  arose  slowly  in  connection  with  simple  experiences  and  passed, 
by  heredity,  to  the  more  highly  organized  being.  Thus  is  explained 
how  synthetic  judgments  arise  which  were  formed  by  our  ancestors 
and  were  born  in  us,  and  are  in  this  sense  a  'priori.  Their  great 
power  is  also  seen  in  this  way,  but  not  their  infallibility. 


RELATIONS   OF   APPLIED   MATHEMATICS  599 

In  saying  that  such  judgments  as  "  everything  is  red  or  is  not  red  " 
are  results  of  experience,  I  do  not  mean  that  every  person  checks  this 
empty  truth  by  experience,  but  that  he  learns  that  his  parents  called 
everything  either  red  or  not  red  and  that  he  preserves  this  nomen- 
clature. 

It  might  seem  as  if  we  had  gone  somewhat  deeply  into  philosophical 
questions,  but  I  believe  that  the  views  we  have  reached  could  not 
have  been  attained  in  a  shorter  and  simpler  manner.  For  we  have 
reached  an  impartial  judgment  how  the  question  of  the  atomistic 
structure  of  matter  is  to  be  viewed.  We  shall  not  invoke  the  law  of 
thought  that  there  is  no  limit  to  the  divisibility  of  matter.  This  law 
is  of  no  more  value  than  if  a  naive  person  were  to  say  that  no  matter 
where  he  went  upon  the  earth  the  plumb-line  directions  seemed 
always  to  be  parallel  and  therefore  there  were  no  antipodes. 

On  the  one  hand  we  shall  start  from  facts  only,  and  on  the  other 
we  shall  take  nothing  into  consideration  except  the  effort  to  attain 
to  the  most  adequate  expression  of  these  facts. 

Regarding  the  first  point,  the  numerous  facts  of  the  theory  of 
heat,  of  chemistry,  of  crystallography,  show  that  bodies  which  are 
apparently  continuous  do  not  by  any  means  fill  the  entire  volume 
indistinguishably  and  uniformly  with  matter.  Indeed,  it  appears 
that  the  space  which  they  occupy  is  filled  with  innumerably  many 
individuals,  molecules,  and  atoms,  which  are  extraordinarily  small, 
but  not  infinitely  small  in  the  mathematical  sense.  Their  sizes  can 
be  computed  in  different  manners  and  always  with  the  same  result. 

The  fruitfulness  of  this  line  of  thought  has  been  verified  in  the 
most  recent  time.  All  the  phenomena  which  are  observed  with  the 
cathode  rays,  the  Becquerel  rays,  etc.,  indicate  that  we  are  dealing 
with  diminutive,  moving  particles,  electrons.  After  a  vigorous 
battle,  this  view  vanquished  completely  the  opposing  explanation  of 
these  phenomena  by  the  theory  of  undulations.  Not  only  did  the 
former  theory  give  a  better  explanation  of  the  previously  known 
facts,  it  inspired  new  experiments  and  permitted  the  prediction  of 
unknown  phenomena,  and  thus  it  developed  into  an  atomistic  theory 
of  electricity.  If  it  continue  to  develop  with  the  same  success  as 
in  past  years,  if  phenomena,  such  as  the  one  observed  by  Ramsay 
on  the  transmutation  of  radium  into  helium,  do  not  remain  isolated, 
this  theory  promises  deductions  concerning  the  nature  and  structure 
of  atoms  as  yet  undreamed  of.  Computation  shows  that  electrons  are 
much  smaller  than  the  atoms  of  ponderable  matter;  and  the  hypo- 
thesis that  the  atoms  are  built  up  of  many  elements,  as  well  as 
various  interesting  views  on  the  character  and  structure  of  this  com- 
position, is  to-day  on  every  tongue.  The  word  atom  should  not 
lead  us  into  error,  it  comes  from  a  past  time;  no  physicist  ascribes 
indivisibility  to  the  atoms. 


600  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

It  is  not  my  intention  to  confine  the  thought  merely  to  the  above 
facts  and  their  resulting  consequences;  these  are  not  sufficient  to 
carry  through  the  question  as  to  the  finite  or  infinite  divisibility 
of  matter.  If  we  are  going  to  think  of  the  atoms  of  chemistry  as 
made  up  of  electrons,  what  would  hinder  us  from  considering  the 
electrons  as  particles  filled  with  rarefied,,  continuous  matter?  We 
shall  adhere  faithfully  to  the  previously  developed  philosophical 
principles  and  shall  examine  in  the  most  unhampered  manner  the 
concepts  themselves  in  order  to  express  them  in  a  consistent  and 
most  useful  form. 

It  appears  now,  that  we  are  unable  to  define  the  infinite  in  any  other 
way  except  as  the  limit  of  continually  increasing  magnitudes,  at 
least  no  one  has  hitherto  been  able  to  set  up  any  other  intelligible 
conception  of  the  infinite.  Should  we  desire  a  verbal  picture  of  the 
continuum,  we  must  first  think  of  a  large  finite  number  of  particles 
which  are  endowed  with  certain  properties  and  study  the  totality 
of  these  particles.  Certain  properties  of  this  totality  may  approach 
a  definite  limit  as  the  number  of  particles  is  increased,  and  their 
size  decreased.  It  can  be  asserted,  concerning  these  properties,  that 
they  belong  to  the  continuum,  and  it  is  my  opinion  that  this  is  the 
only  self-consistent  definition  of  a  continuum  which  is  endowed 
with  certain  properties. 

The  question  if  matter  is  composed  of  atoms  or  is  continuous 
becomes  then  the  question  if  the  observed  properties  are  accurately 
satisfied  by  the  assumption  of  an  exceedingly  great  number  of 
such  particles  or,  by  increasing  number,  their  limit.  We  have  not 
indeed  answered  the  old  philosophical  question,  but  we  are  cured  of 
the  effort  to  answer  it  in  a  senseless  and  hopeless  manner.  The 
thought-process,  that  we  must  investigate  the  properties  of  a  finite 
totality  and  then  let  the  number  of  members  of  this  totality  increase 
greatly,  remains  the  same  in  both  cases.  It  is  nothing  other  than 
the  abbreviated  expression  in  algebraic  symbols  of  exactly  the  same 
thought  when,  as  often  happens,  differential  equations  are  made 
the  basis  of  a  mathematical-physical  theory. 

The  members  of  the  totality  which  we  select  as  the  picture  of  the 
material  body  cannot  be  thought  of  as  absolutely  at  rest,  for  there 
would  then  be  no  motion  of  any  kind,  nor  can  the  members  be  thought 
of  as  relatively  at  rest  in  one  and  the  same  body,  for  in  this  case  it 
would  be  impossible  to  account  for  the  fluids.  No  effort  has  been 
made  to  subject  them  to  anything  more  than  to  the  general  laws 
of  mechanics.  In  order  to  explain  nature  we  shall  therefore  select 
a  totality  of  an  exceedingly  large  number  of  very  minute  funda- 
mental individuals  which  are  constantly  in  motion,  and  which  are 
subject  to  the  laws  of  mechanics.  But  an  objection  is  raised  that 
will  be  an  appropriate  introduction  to  the  final  considerations  of 


RELATIONS   OF   APPLIED   MATHEMATICS  601 

this  lecture.  The  fundamental  equations  of  mechanics  do  not  alter 
their  form  in  the  slightest  way  when  the  algebraic  sign  of  the  time  is 
changed.  All  pure  mechanical  events  can  therefore  occur  equally 
well  in  one  sense  as  in  its  opposite,  that  is,  in  the  sense  of  increasing 
time  or  of  diminishing  time.  We  remark,  however,  that  in  ordinary 
Hfe  future  and  past  do  not  coincide  as  completely  as  the  directions 
right  and  left,  but  that  the  two  are  distinctly  different. 

This  becomes  still  more  definite  by  means  of  the  second  law  of  the 
mechanical  theory  of  heat,  which  asserts  that  when  an  arbitrary 
system  of  bodies  is  left  to  itself,  uninfluenced  by  other  bodies,  the 
sense  in  which  changes  of  condition  occur  can  be  assigned.  A  certain 
f miction  of  the  condition  of  all  the  bodies,  the  entropy,  can  be 
determined,  which  is  such  that  every  change  that  occurs  must  be  in 
the  sense  of  carrying  with  it  an  increase  of  this  function;  thus, 
with  increasing  time  the  entropy  increases.  This  law  is  indeed  an 
abstraction,  just  as  the  principle  of  Galileo;  for  it  is  impossible,  in 
strict  rigor,  to  isolate  a  system  of  bodies  from  all  others.  But  since 
it  has  given  correct  results  hitherto,  in  connection  with  all  the  other 
laws,  we  assume  it  to  be  correct,  just  as  in  the  case  of  the  principle  of 
Galileo. 

It  follows  from  this  law  that  every  closed  system  of  bodies  must 
tend  toward  a  definite  final  condition  for  which  the  entropy  is  a 
maximum.  The  outcome  of  this  law,  that  the  universe  must  come 
to  a  final  state  in  which  nothing  more  can  occur,  has  caused  aston- 
ishment; but  this  outcome  is  only  comprehensible  on  the  assump- 
tion that  the  universe  is  finite  and  subject  to  the  second  law  of  the 
mechanical  theory  of  heat.  If  one  regards  the  universe  as  infinite, 
the  above-mentioned  difficulties  of  thought  arise  again  if  one  does 
not  consider  the  infinite  as  a  mere  limit  of  the  finite.  Since  there  is 
nothing  analogous  to  the  second  law  in  the  differential  equations 
of  mechanics,  it  follows  that  it  can  be  represented  mechanically  only 
by  the  initial  conditions.  In  order  to  find  the  assumptions  suit- 
able for  this  purpose,  we  must  reflect  that,  to  explain  the  appar- 
ent continuity  of  bodies,  we  had  to  assume  that  every  family 
of  atoms,  or  more  generally,  of  mechanical  individuals,  existed  in 
incredibly  many  different  initial  positions.  In  order  to  treat  this 
assumption  mathematically,  a  new  science  was  founded  whose  pro- 
blem is,  not  the  study  of  the  motion  of  a  single  mechanical  system, 
but  of  the  properties  of  complexes  of  very  many  mechanical  systems 
which  begin  with  a  great  variety  of  initial  conditions.  The  task  of 
systematizing  this  science,  of  compiling  it  into  a  large  book,  and  of 
giving  it  a  characteristic  name,  was  executed  by  one  of  the  greatest 
American  scholars,  and  in  regard  to  abstract  thinking,  purely  theo- 
retic investigation,  perhaps  the  greatest,  Willard  Gibbs,  the  recently 
deceased  professor  at  Yale  University.    He  called  this  science  statis- 


602  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

tical  mechanics,  and  it  falls  naturally  into  two  parts.  The  first  in- 
vestigates the  conditions  under  which  the  outwardly  visible  proper- 
ties of  a  complex  of  very  many  mechanical  individuals  is  not  in  any 
wise  altered;  this  first  part  I  shall  call  statistical  statics.  The  sec- 
ond part  investigates  the  gradual  changes  of  these  outwardly  visible 
properties  when  those  conditions  are  not  fulfilled;  it  may  be  called 
statistical  dynamics.  At  this  point  we  may  allude  to  the  broad  view 
which  is  opened  by  applying  this  science  to  the  statistics  of  ani- 
mated beings,  of  human  society,  of  sociology,  etc.,  and  not  merely 
upon  mechanical  particles.  A  development  of  the  details  of  this 
science  would  only  be  possible  in  a  series  of  lectures  and  by  means 
of  mathematical  formulas.  Apart  from  mathematical  difficulties  it  is 
not  free  from  difficulties  of  principle.  It  is  based  upon  the  theory 
of  probabilities.  The  latter  is  as  exact  as  any  other  branch  of  mathe- 
matics if  the  concept  of  equal  probabilities,  which  cannot  be  de- 
duced from  the  other  fundamental  notions,  is  assumed.  It  is  here 
as  in  the  method  of  least  squares  which  is  only  free  from  objection 
when  certain  definite  assumptions  are  made  concerning  the  equal 
probability  of  elementary  errors.  The  existence  of  this  fundamental 
difficulty  explains  why  the  simplest  result  of  statistical  statics,  the 
proof  of  Maxwell's  speed  law  among  the  molecules  of  a  gas,  is  still 
being  disputed. 

The  theorems  of  statistical  mechanics  are  rigorous  consequences 
of  the  assumptions  and  will  always  remain  valid,  just  as  all  well- 
founded  mathematical  theorems.  But  its  application  to  the  events 
of  nature  is  the  prototype  of  a  physical  hypothesis.  Starting  from 
the  simplest  fundamental  assumption  of  the  equal  probabilities,  we 
find  that  aggregates  of  very  many  individuals  behave  quite  ana- 
logously as  experience  shows  of  the  material  world.  Progressive  or 
visible  rotary  motion  must  always  go  over  into  invisible  motion  of 
the  minutest  particles,  into  heat,  as  Helmholtz  characteristically 
says:  ordered  motion  tends  always  to  go  over  into  not  ordered 
motion;  the  mixture  of  different  substances  as  well  as  of  different 
temperatures,  the  points  of  greater  or  less  intense  molecular 
motion,  must  always  tend  toward  homogeneity.  That  this  mixture 
was  not  complete  from  the  start,  that  the  universe  began  in  such 
an  improbable  state,  belongs  to  the  fundamental  hypotheses  of  the 
entire  theory;  and  it  may  be  said  that  the  reason  for  this  is  as  little 
known  as  the  reason  why  the  universe  is  just  so  and  not  otherwise. 
But  we  may  take  a  different  point  of  view.  Conditions  of  great  mix- 
ture and  great  differences  in  temperature  are  not  absolutely  impos- 
sible according  to  the  theory  but  are  very  highly  improbable.  If  the 
universe  be  considered  as  large  enough  there  will  be,  according  to  the 
laws  of  probability,  here  and  there  places  of  the  size  of  fixed  stars, 
of  altogether  improbable  distributions.    The  development  of  such 


RELATIONS  OF  APPLIED  MATHEMATICS  603 

a  spot  would  be  one-sided  both  in  its  structure  and  subsequent  dis- 
solution. Were  there  thinking  beings  at  such  a  spot  their  impressions 
of  time  would  be  the  same  as  ours,  although  the  course  of  events  in 
the  universe  as  a  whole  would  not  be  one-sided.  The  above-developed 
theory  does  indeed  go  boldly  beyond  our  experience,  but  it  has  the 
merit  which  every  such  theory  should  have  of  showing  us  the  facts 
of  experience  in  an  entirely  new  light  and  of  inspiring  us  to  new 
thought  and  reflection.  In  contradistinction  to  the  first  fundamental 
law,  the  second  one  is  merely  based  on  probability,  as  Gibbs  pointed 
out  in  the  '70's  of  the  last  century. 

I  have  not  avoided  philosophical  questions,  in  the  firm  hope  that 
cooperation  between  philosophy  and  natural  science  wiU  give  new 
sustenance  to  both;  indeed,  that  only  in  this  manner  a  consistent 
argument  can  be  carried  through.  I  agree  with  Schiller  when  he 
says  to  the  scientists  and  philosophers  of  his  day, "  Let  there  be  strife 
between  you,  and  the  union  wiU  come  speedily;"  I  believe  that  the 
time  for  this  union  has  now  arrived. 


THE  PRINCIPLES    OF    MATHEMATICAL    PHYSICS 

BY   JULES    HENRI    POINCARE 

(Translated  from  the  French  by  George  Bruce  Halsted,  Kenyan  College) 

[Jules  Henri  Poincare,  Professor  University  of  Paris,  and  the  Polytechnic 
School;  Member  of  Bureau  of  Longitude,  b.  Nancy,  April  29,  1854.  D.Sc. 
August  3, 1879;  D.Sc.  Cambridge  and  Oxford,  1879;  Charge  of  the  Course 
of  the  Faculty  of  Sciences  at  Caen;  Master  of  Conference  of  the  Faculty  of 
Sciences  of  Paris,  1881;  Professor  of  the  same  Faculty,  1886;  Member  of  the 
Institute  of  France,  1887;  Corresponding  Member  of  the  National  Academy 
of  Washington;  Philosophical  Society  of  Philadelphia;  the  Academies  of 
Berlin,  London,  St.  Petersburg,  Vienna,  Rome,  Munich,  Gottingen,  Bologna, 
Turin,  Naples,  Venice,  Amsterdam,  Copenhagen,  Stockholm,  etc.  Written 
books  and  numerous  articles  for  reviews  and  periodicals.] 

What  is  the  actual  state  of  mathematical  physics?  What  are  the 
problems  it  is  led  to  set  itself?  What  is  its  future?  Is  its  orientation 
on  the  point  of  modifying  itself? 

Will  the  aim  and  the  methods  of  this  science  appear  in  ten  years 
to  our  immediate  successors  in  the  same  light  as  to  ourselves;  or, 
on  the  contrary,  are  we  about  to  witness  a  profound  transformation? 
Such  are  the  questions  we  are  forced  to  raise  in  entering  to-day  upon 
our  investigation. 

If  it  is  easy  to  propound  them,  to  answer  is  difficult. 

If  we  feel  ourselves  tempted  to  risk  a  prognostication,  we  have, 
to  resist  this  temptation,  only  to  think  of  all  the  stupidities  the 
most  eminent  savants  of  a  hundred  years  ago  would  have  uttered, 
if  one  had  asked  them  what  the  science  of  the  nineteenth  century 
would  be.  They  would  have  believed  themselves  bold  in  their  pre- 
dictions, yet  after  the  event  how  very  timid  we  should  have  found 
them. 

Mathematical  physics,  we  know,  was  born  of  celestial  mechanics, 
which  engendered  it  at  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century,  at  the 
moment  when  the  latter  was  attaining  its  complete  development. 
During  its  first  years  especially,  the  infant  resembled  in  a  striking 
way  its  mother. 

The  astronomic  universe  is  formed  of  masses,  very  great  without 
doubt,  but  separated  by  intervals  so  immense  that  they  appear  to 
us  only  as  material  points.  These  points  attract  each  other  in  the 
inverse  ratio  of  the  square  of  the  distances,  and  this  attraction  is 
the  sole  force  which  influences  their  movements.  But  if  our  senses 
were  sufficiently  subtle  to  show  us  all  the  details  of  the  bodies  which 
the  physicist  studies,  the  spectacle  we  should  there  discover  would 
scarcely  differ  from  what  the  astronomer  contemplates.  There  also 
we  should  see  material  points,  separated  one  from  another  by  inter- 


PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICAL   PHYSICS        605 

vals  enormous  in  relation  to  their  dimensions,  and  describing  orbits 
following  regular  laws. 

These  infinitesimal  stars  are  the  atoms.  Like  the  stars  properly 
so  called,  they  attract  or  repel  each  other,  and  this  attraction  or  this 
repulsion  directed  following  the  straight  line  which  joins  them,  de- 
pends only  on  the  distance.  The  law  according  to  which  this  force 
varies  as  function  of  the  distance  is  perhaps  not  the  law  of  Newton, 
but  it  is  an  analogous  law;  in  j)lace  of  the  exponent  —  2,  we  have 
probably  a  different  exponent,  and  it  is  from  this  change  of  exponent 
that  springs  aU  the  diversity  of  physical  phenomena,  the  variety  of 
qualities  and  of  sensations,  all  the  world  colored  and  sonorous  which 
surrounds  us,  —  in  a  word,  all  nature. 

Such  is  the  primitive  conception  in  all  its  purity.  It  only  remains 
to  seek  in  the  different  cases  what  value  should  be  given  to  this 
exponent  in  order  to  explain  all  the  facts.  It  is  on  this  model  that 
Laplace,  for  example,  constructed  his  beautiful  theory  of  capillarity; 
he  regards  it  only  as  a  particular  case  of  attraction,  or  as  he  says 
of  universal  gravitation,  and  no  one  is  astonished  to  find  it  in  the 
middle  of  one  of  the  five  volumes  of  the  Mecanique  celeste. 

More  recently  Briot  believed  he  had  penetrated  the  final  secret 
of  optics  in  demonstrating  that  the  atoms  of  ether  attract  each  other 
in  the  inverse  ratio  of  the  sixth  power  of  the  distance;  and  does  not 
Maxwell  himself  say  somewhere  that  the  atoms  of  gases  repel  each 
other  in  the  inverse  ratio  of  the  fifth  power  of  the  distance?  We  have 
the  exponent  —  6,  or  —  5  in  place  of  the  exponent  —  2,  but  it  is 
always  an  exponent. 

Among  the  theories  of  this  period,  one  alone  is  an  exception,  that 
of  Fourier;  in  it  are  indeed  atoms,  acting  at  a  distance  one  upon  the 
other;  they  mutually  transmit  heat,  but  the}^  do  not  attract,  they 
never  budge.  From  this  point  of  view,  the  theory  of  Fourier  must 
have  appeared  to  the  eyes  of  his  contemporaries,  even  to  Fourier 
himself,  as  imperfect  and  provisional. 

This  conception  was  not  without  grandeur;  it  was  seductive,  and 
many  among  us  have  not  finally  renounced  it;  we  know  that  we 
shall  attain  the  ultimate  elements  of  things  only  by  patiently  disen- 
tangling the  complicated  skein  that  our  senses  give  us;  that  it  is 
necessary  to  advance  step  by  step,  neglecting  no  intermediary;  that 
our  fathers  were  wrong  in  wishing  to  skip  stations;  but  we  believe 
that  when  we  shall  have  arrived  at  these  ultimate  elements,  there 
again  wiU  be  found  the  majestic  simplicity  of  celestial  mechanics. 

Neither  has  this  conception  been  useless;  it  has  rendered  us  an 
inestimable  service,  since  it  has  contributed  to  make  precise  in  us 
the  fundamental  notion  of  the  physical  law. 

I  will  explain  myself;  how  did  the  ancients  understand  law?  It 
was  for  them  an  internal  harmony,  static,  so  to  say,  and  immutable; 


606  APPLIED  MATHEMATICS  ' 

or  it  was  like  a  model  that  nature  constrained  herself  to  imitate.  A 
law  for  us  is  not  that  at  all;  it  is  a  constant  relation  between  the 
phenomenon  of  to-day  and  that  of  to-morrow;  in  a  word,  it  is  a 
differential  equation. 

The  ideal  form  of  physical  law  is  the  law  of  Newton  which  first 
covered  it;  and  then  how  has  one  to  adapt  this  form  to  physics? 
by  copying  as  much  as  possible  this  law  of  Newton,  that  is,  in  imi- 
tating celestial  mechanics. 

Nevertheless,  a  day  arrived  when  the  conception  of  central  forces 
no  longer  appeared  sufficient,  and  this  is  the  first  of  those  crises  of 
which  I  just  now  spoke. 

Then  investigators  gave  up  trying  to  penetrate  into  the  detail 
of  the  structure  of  the  universe,  to  isolate  the  pieces  of  this  vast 
mechanism,  to  analyze  one  by  one  the  forces  which  put  them  in 
motion,  and  were  content  to  take  as  guides  certain  general  prin- 
ciples which  have  precisely  for  their  object  the  sparing  us  this  minute 
study. 

How  so?  Suppose  that  we  have  before  us  any  machine;  the  ini- 
tial wheel-work  and  the  final  wheel-work  alone  are  visible,  but  the 
transmission,  the  intermediary  wheels  by  which  the  movement  is 
communicated  from  one  to  the  other  are  hidden  in  the  interior 
and  escape  our  view;  we  do  not  know  whether  the  communication 
is  made  by  gearing  or  by  belts,  by  connecting-rods  or  by  other  dis- 
positives. 

Do  we  say  that  it  is  impossible  for  us  to  understand  anything  about 
this  machine  so  long  as  we  are  not  permitted  to  take  it  to  pieces? 
You  know  well  we  do  not,  and  that  the  principle  of  the  conservation 
of  energy  suffices  to  determine  for  us  the  most  interesting  point.  We 
easily  ascertain  that  the  final  wheel  turns  ten  times  less  quickly  than 
the  initial  wheel,  since  these  two  wheels  are  visible;  we  are  able 
thence  to  conclude  that  a  couple  applied  to  the  one  will  be  balanced 
by  a  couple  ten  times  greater  applied  to  the  other.  For  that  there 
is  no  need  to  penetrate  the  mechanism  of  this  equilibrium  and  to 
know  how  the  forces  compensate  each  other  in  the  interior  of  the 
machine;  it  suffices  to  be  assured  that  this  compensation  cannot  fail 
to  occur. 

Well,  in  regard  to  the  universe,  the  principle  of  the  conservation 
of  energy  is  able  to  render  us  the  same  service.  This  is  also  a  machine, 
much  more  complicated  than  all  those  of  industry,  and  of  which 
almost  all  the  parts  are  profoundly  hidden  from  us;  but  in  observing 
the  movement  of  those  that  we  can  see,  we  are  able,  by  aid  of  this 
principle,  to  draw  conclusions  which  remain  true  whatever  may  be 
the  details  of  the  invisible  mechanism  which  animates  them. 

The  principle  of  the  conservation  of  energy,  or  the  principle  of 
Mayer,  is  certainly  the  most  important,  but  it  is  not  the  only  one; 


PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICAL   PHYSICS        607 

there  are  others  from  which  we  are  able  to  draw  the  same  advantage. 
These  are: 

The  principle  of  Carnot,  or  the  principle  of  the  degradation  of 
energy. 

The  principle  of  Newton,  or  the  principle  of  the  equality  of  action 
and  reaction. 

The  principle  of  relativity,  according  to  which  the  laws  of  phys- 
ical phenomena  should  be  the  same,  whether  for  an  observer 
fixed,  or  for  an  observer  carried  along  in  a  uniform  move- 
ment of  translation;  so  that  we  have  not  and  could  not 
have  any  means  of  discerning  whether  or  not  we  are  carried 
along  in  such  a  motion. 

The  principle  of    the  conservation  of    mass,   or   principle  of 
Lavoisier. 
I  would  add  the  principle  of  least  action. 

The  application  of  these  five  or  six  general  principles  to  the  differ- 
ent physical  phenomena  is  sufficient  for  our  learning  of  them  what 
we  could  reasonably  hope  to  know  of  them. 

The  most  remarkable  example  of  this  new  mathematical  physics 
is,  beyond  contradiction,  Maxwell's  electro-magnetic  theory  of  light. 

We  know  nothing  of  the  ether,  how  its  molecules  are  disposed, 
whether  they  attract  or  repel  each  other;  but  we  know  that  this 
medium  transmits  at  the  same  time  the  optical  perturbations  and 
the  electrical  perturbations;  we  know  that  this  transmission  should 
be  made  conformably  to  the  general  principles  of  mechanics,  and 
that  suffices  us  for  the  establishment  of  the  equations  of  the  electro- 
magnetic field. 

These  principles  are  results  of  experiments  boldly  generalized; 
but  they  seem  to  derive  from  their  generality  itself  an  eminent 
degree  of  certitude. 

In  fact  the  more  general  they  are,  the  more  frequently  one  has 
the  occasion  to  check  them,  and  the  verifications,  in  multiplying 
themselves,  in  taking  forms  the  most  varied  and  the  most  unex- 
pected, finish  by  no  longer  leaving  place  for  doubt. 

Such  is  the  second  phase  of  the  history  of  mathematical  physics, 
and  we  have  not  yet  emerged  from  it. 

Do  we  say  that  the  first  has  been  useless?  that  during  fifty  yearg 
science  went  the  wrong  way,  and  that  there  is  nothing  left  but  to 
forget  so  many  accumulated  efforts  as  vicious  conceptions  condemned 
in  advance  to  non-success? 

Not  the  least  in  the  world ;  the  second  phase  could  not  have  come 
into  existence  without  the  first? 

The  hypothesis  of  central  forces  contained  all  the  principles;  it 
involved  them  as  necessary  consequences;  it  involved  both  the  con- 


608  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

servation  of  energy  and  that  of  masses,  and  the  equahty  of  action 
and  reaction;  and  the  law  of  least  action,  which  would  appear,  it 
is  true,  not  as  experimental  verities,  but  as  theorems,  and  of  which 
the  enunciation  would  have  at  the  same  time  a  something  more  pre- 
cise and  less  general  than  under  their  actual  form. 

It  is  the  mathematical  physics  of  our  fathers  which  has  familiar- 
ized us  little  by  little  with  these  divers  principles;  which  has  taught 
us  to  recognize  them  under  the  different  vestments  in  which  they 
disguise  themselves.  One  has  to  compare  them  to  the  data  of  ex- 
perience, to  find  how  it  was  necessary  to  modify  their  enunciation 
so  as  to  adapt  them  to  these  data;  and  by  these  processes  they 
have  been  enlarged  and  consolidated. 

So  we  have  been  led  to  regard  them  as  experimental  verities; 
the  conception  of  central  forces  became  then  a  useless  support,  or 
rather  an  embarrassment,  since  it  made  the  principles  partake  of  its 
hypothetical  character. 

The  frames  have  not  therefore  broken,  because  they  were  elastic; 
but  they  have  enlarged;  our  fathers,  who  established  them,  did  not 
work  in  vain,  and  we  recognize  in  the  science  of  to-day  the  general 
traits  of  the  sketch  which  they  traced. 

Are  we  about  to  enter  now  upon  the  eve  of  a  second  crisis?  Are 
these  principles  on  which  we  have  built  all  about  to  crumble  away 
in  their  turn?  For  some  time,  this  may  well  have  been  asked. 

In  hearing  me  speak  thus,  you  think  without  doubt  of  radium, 
that  grand  revolutionist  of  the  present  time,  and  in  fact  I  will  come 
back  to  it  presently;  but  there  is  something  else. 

It  is  not  alone  the  conservation  of  energy  which  is  in  question; 
all  the  other  principles  are  equally  in  danger,  as  we  shall  see  in  pass- 
ing them  successively  in  review. 

Let  us  commence  with  the  principle  of  Carnot.  This  is  the  only 
one  which  does  not  present  itself  as  an  immediate  consequence  of 
the  hypothesis  of  central  forces;  more  than  that,  it  seems,  if  not 
directly  to  contradict  that  hypothesis,  at  least  not  to  be  reconciled 
with  it  without  a  certain  effort. 

If  physical  phenomena  were  due  exclusively  to  the  movements 
of  atoms  whose  mutual  attraction  depended  only  on  the  distance, 
it  seems  that  all  these  phenomena  should  be  reversible;  if  all  the 
initial  velocities  were  reversed,  these  atoms,  always  subjected  to 
the  same  forces,  ought  to  go  over  their  trajectories  in  the  contrary 
sense,  just  as  the  earth  would  describe  in  the  retrograde  sense  this 
same  elliptic  orbit  which  it  describes  in  the  direct  sense,  if  the  initial 
conditions  of  its  movement  had  been  reversed.  On  this  account,  if 
a  physical  phenomenon  is  possible,  the  inverse  phenomenon  should 
be  equally  so,  and  one  should  be  able  to  reascend  the  course  of 
time. 


PRINCIPLES  OF  MATHEMATICAL   PHYSICS        609 

But  it  is  not  so  in  nature,  and  this  is  precisely  what  the  principle 
of  Carnot  teaches  us;  heat  can  pass  from  the  warm  body  to  the  cold 
body;  it  is  impossible  afterwards  to  make  it  reascend  the  inverse 
way  and  reestablish  differences  of  temperature  which  have  been 
effaced. 

Motion  can  be  wholly  dissipated  and  transformed  into  heat  by 
friction;  the  contrary  transformation  can  never  be  made  except  in 
a  partial  manner. 

We  have  striven  to  reconcile  this  apparent  contradiction.  If  the 
world  tends  toward  uniformity,  this  is  not  because  its  ultimate  parts, 
at  first  unlike,  tend  to  become  less  and  less  different,  it  is  because, 
shifting  at  hazard,  they  end  by  blending.  For  an  eye  which  should 
distinguish  all  the  elements,  the  variety  would  remain  always  as 
great,  each  grain  of  this  dust  preserves  its  originality  and  does  not 
model  itself  on  its  neighbors;  but  as  the  blend  becomes  more  and 
more  intimate,  our  gross  senses  perceive  no  more  than  the  uniform- 
ity. Behold  why,  for  example,  temperatures  tend  to  a  level,  without 
the  possibility  of  turning  backwards. 

A  drop  of  wine  falls  into  a  glass  of  water;  whatever  may  be  the 
law  of  the  internal  movements  of  the  liquid,  we  soon  see  it  colored 
to  a  uniform  rosy  tint,  and  from  this  moment,  however  well  we 
may  shake  the  vase,  the  wine  and  the  water  do  not  seem  capable  of 
further  separation.  Observe  what  would  be  the  type  of  the  reversible 
physical  phenomenon:  to  hide  a  grain  of  barley  in  a  cup  of  wheat 
is  easy;  afterwards  to  find  it  again  and  get  it  out  is  practically  im- 
possible. 

All  this  Maxwell  and  Boltzmann  have  explained;  the  one  who  has 
seen  it  most  clearly,  in  a  book  too  little  read  because  it  is  a  little 
difficult  to  read,  is  Gibbs,  in  his  Elementary  Principles  of  Statistical 
Mechanics. 

For  those  who  take  this  point  of  view,  the  principle  of  Carnot  is 
only  an  imperfect  principle,  a  sort  of  concession  to  the  infirmity  of 
our  senses;  it  is  because  our  eyes  are  too  gross  that  we  do  not  dis- 
tinguish the  elements  of  the  blend;  it  is  because  our  hands  are  too 
gross  that  we  cannot  force  them  to  separate;  the  imaginary  demon 
of  Maxwell,  who  is  able  to  sort  the  molecules  one  by  one,  could  well 
constrain  the  world  to  return  backward.  Can  it  return  of  itself?  That 
is  not  impossible;  that  is  only  infinitely  improbable. 

The  chances  are  that  we  should  long  await  the  concourse  of  cir- 
cumstances which  would  permit  a  retrogradation,  but  soon  or  late 
they  would  be  realized,  after  years  whose  number  it  would  take 
millions  of  figures  to  write. 

These  reservations,  however,  all  remained  theoretic  and  were  not 
very  disquieting,  and  the  principle  of  Carnot  retained  all  its  practical 
value. 


610  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

But  here  the  scene  changes. 

The  biologist,  armed  with  his  microscope,  long  ago  noticed  in  his 
preparations  disorderly  movements  of  little  particles  in  suspension: 
this  is  the  Brownian  movement;  he  first  thought  this  was  a  vital 
phenomenon,  but  he  soon  saw  that  the  inanimate  bodies  danced  with 
no  less  ardor  than  the  others;  then  he  turned  the  matter  over  to  the 
physicists.  Unhappily,  the  physicists  remained  long  uninterested  in 
this  question;  the  light  is  focused  to  illuminate  the  microscopic  pre- 
paration, thought  they;  with  light  goes  heat;  hence  inequalities  of 
temperature  and  interior  currents  produce  the  movements  in  the 
liquid  of  which  we  speak. 

M.  Gouy,  however,  looked  more  closely,  and  he  saw,  or  thought 
he  saw,  that  this  explanation  is  untenable,  that  the  movements 
become  more  brisk  as  the  particles  are  smaller,  but  that  they  are  not 
influenced  by  the  mode  of  illumination. 

If,  then,  these  movements  never  cease,  or  rather  are  reborn  with- 
out ceasing,  without  borrowing  anything  from  an  external  source 
of  energy,  what  ought  we  to  believe?  To  be  sure,  we  should  not 
renounce  our  belief  in  the  conservation  of  energy,  but  we  see  under 
our  eyes  now  motion  transformed  into  heat  by  friction,  now  heat 
changed  inversely  into  motion,  and  that  without  loss  since  the  move- 
ment lasts  forever.   This  is  the  contrary  of  the  principle  of  Carnot. 

If  this  be  so,  to  see  the  world  return  backward,  we  no  longer 
have  need  of  the  infinitely  subtle  eye  of  Maxwell's  demon;  our 
microscope  suffices  us.  Bodies  too  large,  those,  for  example,  which 
are  a  tenth  of  a  millimeter,  are  hit  from  all  sides  by  moving  atoms, 
but  they  do  not  budge,  because  these  shocks  are  very  numerous  and 
the  law  of  chance  makes  them  compensate  each  other:  but  the 
smaller  particles  receive  too  few  shocks  for  this  compensation  to 
take  place  with  certainty  and  are  incessantly  knocked  about.  And 
thus  already  one  of  our  principles  is  in  peril. 

We  come  to  the  principle  of  relativity :  this  not  only  is  confirmed 
by  daily  experience,  not  only  is  it  a  necessary  consequence  of  the 
hypothesis  of  central  forces,  but  it  is  imposed  in  an  irresistible  way 
upon  our  good  sense,  and  yet  it  also  is  battered. 

Consider  two  electrified  bodies;  though  they  seem  to  us  at  rest, 
they  are  both  carried  along  by  the  motion  of  the  earth;  an  electric 
charge  in  motion,  Rowland  has  taught  us,  is  equivalent  to  a  current; 
these  two  charged  bodies  are,  therefore,  equivalent  to  two  parallel 
currents  of  the  same  sense  and  these  two  currents  should  attract 
each  other.  In  measuring  this  attraction,  we  measure  the  velocity 
of  the  earth;  not  its  velocity  in  relation  to  the  sun  or  the  fixed  stars, 
but  its  absolute  velocity. 

I  know  it  will  be  said  that  it  is  not  its  absolute  velocity  that 
is  measured,  but  its  velocity  in  relation  to  the  ether.    How  unsatis- 


PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICAL   PHYSICS        611 

factory  that  is!  Is  it  not  evident  that  from  a  principle  so  under- 
stood we  could  no  longer  get  anything?  It  could  no  longer  tell  us 
anything  just  because  it  would  no  longer  fear  any  contradiction. 

If  we  succeed  in  measuring  anything,  we  should  always  be  free 
to  say  that  this  is  not  the  absolute  velocity  in  relation  to  the  ether, 
it  might  always  be  the  velocity  in  relation  to  some  new  unknown 
fluid  with  which  we  might  fill  space. 

Indeed,  experience  has  taken  on  itself  to  ruin  this  interpretation 
of  the  principle  of  relativity;  all  attempts  to  measure  the  velocity 
of  the  earth  in  relation  to  the  ether  have  led  to  negative  results. 
This  time  experimental  physics  has  been  more  faithful  to  the  prin- 
ciple than  mathematical  physics;  the  theorists,  to  put  in  accord 
their  other  general  views,  would  not  have  spared  it;  but  experiment 
has  been  stubborn  in  confirming  it. 

The  means  have  been  varied  in  a  thousand  ways  and  finally 
Michelson  has  pushed  precision  to  its  last  limits;  nothing  has  come 
of  it.  It  is  precisely  to  explain  this  obstinacy  that  the  mathematicians 
are  forced  to-day  to  employ  all  their  ingenuity. 

Their  task  was  not  easy,  and  if  Lorentz  has  gotten  through  it, 
it  is  only  by  accumulating  hypotheses. 

The  most  ingenious  idea  has  been  that  of  local  time. 

Imagine  two  observers  who  wish  to  adjust  their  watches  by 
optical  signals;  they  exchange  signals,  but  as  they  know  that  the 
transmission  of  light  is  not  instantaneous,  they  take  care  to  cross 
them. 

When  the  station  B  perceives  the  signal  from  the  station  A,  its 
clock  should  not  mark  the  same  hour  as  that  of  the  station  A  at  the 
moment  of  sending  the  signal,  but  this  hour  augmented  by  a  con- 
stant representing  the  duration  of  the  transmission.  Suppose,  for 
example,  that  the  station  A  sends  its  signal  when  its  clock  marks 
the  hour  0,  and  that  the  station  B  perceives  it  when  its  clock  marks 
the  hour  t.  The  clocks  are  adjusted  if  the  slowness  equal  to  t  repre- 
sents the  duration  of  the  transmission,  and  to  verify  it  the  station  B 
sends  in  its  turn  a  signal  when  its  clock  marks  0;  then  the  station  A 
should  perceive  it  when  its  clock  marks  t.  The  time-pieces  are  then 
adjusted.  And  in  fact,  they  mark  the  same  hour  at  the  same  phys- 
ical instant,  but  on  one  condition,  namely,  that  the  two  stations  are 
fixed.  In  the  contrary  case  the  duration  of  the  transmission  mil  not 
be  the  same  in  the  two  senses,  since  the  station  A,  for  example, 
moves  forward  to  meet  the  optical  perturbation  emanating  from  B, 
while  the  station  B  flies  away  before  the  perturbation  emanating 
from  A.  The  watches  adjusted  in  that  manner  do  not  mark,  there- 
fore, the  true  time;  they  mark  what  one  may  caU  the  local  time,  so 
that  one  of  them  goes  slow  on  the  other.  It  matters  little,  since  we 
have  no  means  of  perceiving  it.    All  the  phenomena  which  happen 


612  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

at  A,  for  example,  will  be  late,  but  all  will  be  equally  so,  and  the 
observer  who  ascertains  them  will  not  perceive  it,  since  his  watch  is 
slow;  so,  as  the  principle  of  relativity  would  have  it,  he  will  have  no 
means  of  knowing  whether  he  is  at  rest  or  in  absolute  motion. 

Unhappily,  that  does  not  suffice,  and  complementary  hypotheses 
are  necessary;  it  is  necessary  to  admit  that  bodies  in  motion  undergo 
a  uniform  contraction  in  the  sense  of  the  motion.  One  of  the  dia- 
meters of  the  earth,  for  example,  is  shrunk  by  200  000  000  ^^  conse- 
quence of  the  motion  of  our  planet,  while  the  other  diameter  retains 
its  normal  length.  Thus,  the  last  little  differences  find  themselves 
compensated.  And  then  there  still  is  the  hypothesis  about  forces. 
Forces,  whatever  be  their  origin,  gravity  as  well  as  elasticity,  would 
be  reduced  in  a  certain  proportion  in  a  world  animated  by  a  uniform 
translation;  or,  rather,  this  would  happen  for  the  components  perpen- 
dicular to  the  translation;  the  components  parallel  would  not  change. 

Resume,  then,  our  example  of  two  electrified  bodies;  these  bodies 
repel  each  other,  but  at  the  same  time  if  all  is  carried  along  in  a 
uniform  translation,  they  are  equivalent  to  two  parallel  currents  of 
the  same  sense  which  attract  each  other.  This  electro-dynamic 
attraction  diminishes,  therefore,  the  electro-static  repulsion,  and  the 
total  repulsion  is  more  feeble  than  if  the  two  bodies  were  at  rest. 
But  since  to  measure  this  repulsion  we  must  balance  it  by  another 
force,  and  all  these  other  forces  are  reduced  in  the  same  proportion, 
we  perceive  nothing. 

Thus,  all  is  arranged,  but  are  all  the  doubts  dissipated? 

What  would  happen  if  one  could  communicate  by  non-luminous 
signals  whose  velocity  of  propagation  differed  from  that  of  light? 
If,  after  having  adjusted  the  watches  by  the  optical  procedure,  one 
wished  to  verify  the  adjustment  by  the  aid  of  these  new  signals, 
then  would  appear  divergences  which  would  render  evident  the  com- 
mon translation  of  the  two  stations.  And  are  such  signals  incon- 
ceivable, if  we  admit  with  Laplace  that  universal  gravitation  is 
transmitted  a  million  times  more  rapidly  than  light? 

Thus,  the  principle  of  relativity  has  been  valiantly  defended  in 
these  latter  times,  but  the  very  energy  of  the  defense  proves  how 
serious  was  the  attack. 

Let  us  speak  now  of  the  principle  of  Newton,  on  the  equality  of 
action  and  reaction. 

This  is  intimately  bound  up  with  the  preceding,  and  it  seemB 
indeed  that  the  fall  of  the  one  would  involve  that  of  the  other. 
Thus  we  should  not  be  astonished  to  find  here  the  same  difficulties. 

Electrical  phenomena,  we  think,  are  due  to  the  displacements  of 
little  charged  particles,  called  electrons,  immersed  in  the  medium 
that  we  call  ether.  The  movements  of  these  electrons  produce  per- 
turbations in  the  neighboring  ether;   these  perturbations  propagate 


PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICAL   PHYSICS       613 

themselves  in  every  direction  with  the  velocity  of  light,  and  in  turn 
other  electrons,  originally  at  rest,  are  made  to  vibrate  when  the 
perturbation  reaches  the  parts  of  the  ether  which  touch  them. 

The  electrons,  therefore,  act  upon  one  another,  but  this  action  is 
not  direct,  it  is  accomplished  through  the  ether  as  intermediary. 

Under  these  conditions  can  there  be  compensation  between  action 
and  reaction,  at  least  for  an  observer  who  should  take  account 
only  of  the  movements  of  matter,  that  is  to  say,  of  the  electrons,  and 
who  should  be  ignorant  of  those  of  the  ether  that  he  could  not  see? 
Evidently  not.  Even  if  the  compensation  should  be  exact,  it  could 
not  be  simultaneous.  The  perturbation  is  propagated  with  a  finite 
velocity;  it,  therefore,  reaches  the  second  electron  only  when  the 
first  has  long  ago  entered  upon  its  rest. 

This  second  electron,  therefore,  will  undergo,  after  a  delay,  the 
action  of  the  first,  but  certainly  it  will  not  react  on  this,  since  around 
this  first  electron  nothing  any  longer  budges. 

The  analysis  of  the  facts  permits  us  to  be  still  more  precise.  Imagine 
for  example,  a  Hertzian  generator,  like  those  employed  in  wireless 
telegraphy;  it  sends  out  energy  in  every  direction;  but  we  can 
provide  it  with  a  parabolic  mirror,  as  Hertz  did  with  his  smallest 
generators,  so  as  to  send  all  the  energy  produced  in  a  single  direction. 

What  happens,  then,  according  to  the  theory?  It  is  that  the 
apparatus  recoils  as  if  it  were  a  gun  and  as  if  the  energy  it  has 
projected  were  a  bullet;  and  that  is  contrary  to  the  principle  of 
Newton,  since  our  projectile  here  has  no  mass,  it  is  not  matter,  it 
is  energy. 

It  is  still  the  same,  moreover,  with  a  beacon  light  provided  with 
a  reflector,  since  light  is  nothing  but  a  perturbation  of  the  electro- 
magnetic field.  This  beacon  light  should  recoil  as  if  the  light  it 
sends  out  were  a  projectile.  What  is  the  force  that  this  recoil  should 
produce?  It  is  what  one  has  called  the  Maxwell-Bartholdi  pressure. 
It  is  very  minute,  and  it  has  been  difficult  to  put  it  into  evidence 
even  with  the  most  sensitive  radiometers;  but  it  suffices  that  it  exists. 

If  all  the  energy  issuing  from  our  generator  falls  on  a  receiver, 
this  will  act  as  if  it  had  received  a  mechanical  shock,  which  will 
represent  in  a  sense  the  compensation  of  the  recoil  of  the  generator; 
the  reaction  will  be  equal  to  the  action,  but  it  will  not  be  simulta- 
neous; the  receiver  will  move  on  but  not  at  the  moment  when  the 
generator  recoils.  If  the  energy  propagates  itself  indefinitely  with- 
out encountering  a  receiver,  the  compensation  will  never  be  made. 

Do  we  say  that  the  space  which  separates  the  generator  from 
the  receiver  and  which  the  perturbation  must  pass  over  in  going 
from  the  one  to  the  other  is  not  void,  that  it  is  full  not  only  of  ether, 
but  of  air;  or  even  in  the  interplanetary  spaces  of  some  fluid  subtle 
but  still  ponderable;   that  this  matter  undergoes  the  shock  like  the 


614  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

receiver  at  the  moment  when  the  energy  reaches  it,  and  recoils  in  its 
turn  when  the  perturbation  quits  it?  That  would  save  the  principle 
of  Newton,  but  that  is  not  true. 

If  energy  in  its  diffusion  remained  always  attached  to  some  ma- 
terial substratum,  then  matter  in  motion  would  carry  along  light 
with  it,  and  Fizeau  has  demonstrated  that  it  does  nothing  of  the 
sort,  at  least  for  air.  This  is  what  Michelson  and  Morley  have  since 
confirmed. 

One  may  suppose  also  that  the  movements  of  matter,  properly 
so  called,  are  exactly  compensated  by  those  of  the  ether;  but  that 
would  lead  us  to  the  same  reflections  as  just  now.  The  principle  so 
extended  would  explain  everything,  since  whatever  might  be  the 
visible  movements,  we  should  always  have  the  power  of  imagining 
hypothetical  movements  which  compensated  them. 

But  if  it  is  able  to  explain  everything,  this  is  because  it  does 
not  permit  us  to  foresee  anything;  it  does  not  enable  us  to  decide 
between  different  possible  hypotheses,  since  it  explains  everything 
beforehand.    It  therefore  becomes  useless. 

And  then  the  suppositions  that  it  would  be  necessary  to  make 
on  the  movements  of  the  ether  are  not  very  satisfactory. 

If  the  electric  charges  double,  it  would  be  natural  to  imagine 
that  the  velocities  of  the  divers  atoms  of  ether  double  also,  and  for 
the  compensation,  it  would  be  necessary  that  the  mean  velocity  of 
the  ether  quadruple. 

This  is  why  I  have  long  thought  that  these  consequences  of 
theory,  contrary  to  the  principle  of  Newton,  would  end  some  day 
by  being  abandoned,  and  yet  the  recent  experiments  on  the  move- 
ments of  the  electrons  issuing  from  radium  seem  rather  to  confirm 
them. 

I  arrive  at  the  principle  of  Lavoisier  on  the  conservation  of  masses : 
in  truth  this  is  one  not  to  be  touched  without  unsettling  all  mechanics. 

And  now  certain  persons  believe  that  it  seems  true  to  us  only 
because  we  consider  in  mechanics  merely  moderate  velocities,  but 
that  it  would  cease  to  be  true  for  bodies  animated  by  velocities  com- 
parable to  that  of  light.  These  velocities,  it  is  now  believed,  have 
been  realized;  the  cathode  rays  or  those  of  radium  may  be  formed 
of  very  minute  particles  or  of  electrons  which  are  displaced  with 
velocities  smaller  no  doubt  than  that  of  light,  but  which  might  be  its 
one  tenth  or  one  third. 

These  rays  can  be  deflected,  whether  by  an  electric  field,  or  by 
a  magnetic  field,  and  we  are  able  by  comparing  these  deflections,  to 
measure  at  the  same  time  the  velocity  of  the  electrons  and  their  mass 
(or  rather  the  relation  of  their  mass  to  their  charge).  But  when 
it  was  seen  that  these  velocities  approached  that  of  light,  it  was 
decided  that  a  correction  was  necessary. 


PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICAL   PHYSICS        615 

These  molecules,  being  electrified,  could  not  be  displaced  with- 
out agitating  the  ether;  to  put  them  in  motion  it  is  necessary  to 
overcome  a  double  inertia,  that  of  the  molecule  itself  and  that  of  the 
ether.  The  total  or  apparent  mass  that  one  measures  is  composed, 
therefore,  of  two  parts:  the  real  or  mechanical  mass  of  the  mole- 
cule and  the  electro-dynamic  mass  representing  the  inertia  of  the 
ether. 

The  calculations  of  Abraham  and  the  experiments  of  Kaufmann 
have  then  shown  that  the  mechanical  mass,  properly  so  called,  is 
null,  and  that  the  mass  of  the  electrons,  or,  at  least,  of  the  negative 
electrons,  is  of  exclusively  electro-dynamic  origin.  This  forces  us  to 
change  the  definition  of  mass;  we  cannot  any  longer  distinguish 
mechanical  mass  and  electro-dynamic  mass,  since  then  the  first  would 
vanish;'  there  is  no  mass  other  than  electro-dynamic  inertia.  But 
in  this  case  the  mass  can  no  longer  be  constant,  it  augments  with  the 
velocity,  and  it  even  depends  on  the  direction,  and  a  body  animated 
by  a  notable  velocity  will  not  oppose  the  same  inertia  to  the  forces 
which  tend  to  defiect  it  from  its  route,  as  to  those  which  tend  to 
accelerate  or  to  retard  its  progress. 

There  is  still  a  resource;  the  ultimate  elements  of  bodies  are 
electrons,  some  charged  negatively,  the  others  charged  positively. 
The  negative  electrons  have  no  mass,  this  is  understood;  but  the 
positive  electrons,  from  the  little  we  know  of  them,  seem  much 
greater.  Perhaps  they  have,  besides  their  electro-dynamic  mass, 
a  true  mechanical  mass.  The  veritable  mass  of  a  body  would,  then, 
be  the  sum  of  the  mechanical  masses  of  its  positive  electrons,  the 
negative  electrons  not  counting;  mass  so  defined  could  still  be  con- 
stant. 

Alas,  this  resource  also  evades  us.  Recall  what  we  have  said 
of  the  principle  of  relativity  and  of  the  efforts  made  to  save  it.  And 
it  is  not  merely  a  principle  which  it  is  a  question  of  saving,  such 
are  the  indubitable  results  of  the  experiments  of  Michelson. 

Lorentz  has  been  obliged  to  suppose  that  all  the  forces,  what- 
ever be  their  origin,  were  affected  with  a  coefficient  in  a  medium 
animated  by  a  uniform  translation;  this  is  not  sufficient;  it  is  still 
necessary,  says  he,  that  the  masses  of  all  the  particles  he  influenced 
by  a  translation  to  the  same  degree  as  the  electro-magnetic  fnasses 
of  the  electrons. 

So  the  mechanical  masses  will  vary  in  accordance  with  the  same 
laws  as  the  electro-dynamic  masses;  they  cannot,  therefore,  be  con- 
stant. 

Need  I  point  out  that  the  fall  of  the  principle  of  Lavoisier  in- 
volves that  of  the  principle  of  Newton?  This  latter  signifies  that 
the  centre  of  gravity  of  an  isolated  system  moves  in  a  straight  line; 
but  if  there  is  no  longer  a  constant  mass,  there  is  no  longer  a  centre 


616  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

of  gravity,  we  no  longer  know  even  what  this  is.  This  is  why  I 
said  above  that  the  experiments  on  the  cathode  rays  appeared  to 
justify  the  doubts  of  Lorentz  on  the  subject  of  the  principle  of 
Newton. 

From  all  these  results,  if  they  are  confirmed,  would  arise  an 
entirely  new  mechanics,  which  would  be,  above  all,  characterized  by 
this  fact,  that  no  velocity  could  surpass  that  of  light,  any  more  than 
any  temperature  could  fall  below  the  zero  absolute,  because  bodies 
would  oppose  an  increasing  inertia  to  the  causes,  which  would  tend 
to  accelerate  their  motion;  and  this  inertia  would  become  infinite 
when  one  approached  the  velocity  of  light. 

Nor  for  an  observer  carried  along  himself  in  a  translation  he 
did  not  suspect  could  any  apparent  velocity  surpass  that  of  light; 
there  would  then  be  a  contradiction,  if  we  recall  that  this  observer 
would  not  use  the  same  clocks  as  a  fixed  observer,  but,  indeed,  clocks 
marking  "local  time." 

Here  we  are  then  facing  a  question  I  content  myself  with  stating. 
If  there  is  no  longer  any  mass,  what  becomes  of  the  law  of  Newton? 

Mass  has  two  aspects,  it  is  at  the  same  time  a  coefficient  of  iner- 
tia and  an  attracting  mass  entering  as  factor  into  Newtonian  attrac- 
tion. If  the  coefficient  of  inertia  is  not  constant,  can  the  attracting 
mass  be?   That  is  the  question. 

At  least,  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  energy  yet  remains 
to  us,  and  this  seems  more  solid.  Shall  I  recall  to  you  how  it  was 
in  its  turn  thrown  into  discredit?  This  event  has  made  more  noise 
than  the  preceding  and  it  is  in  all  the  records. 

From  the  first  works  of  Becquerel,  and,  above  all,  when  the 
Curies  had  discovered  radium,  one  saw  that  every  radio-active  body 
was  an  inexhaustible  source  of  radiations.  Its  activity  would  seem 
to  subsist  without  alteration  throughout  the  months  and  the  years. 
This  was  already  a  strain  on  the  principles;  these  radiations  were  in 
fact  energy,  and  from  the  same  morsel  of  radium  this  issued  and  for- 
ever issued.  But  these  quantities  of  energy  were  too  slight  to  be 
measured;  at  least  one  believed  so  and  was  not  much  disquieted. 

The  scene  changed  when  Curie  bethought  himself  to  put  radium 
into  a  calorimeter;  it  was  seen  then  that  the  quantity  of  heat  in- 
cessantly created  was  very  notable. 

The  explanations  proposed  were  numerous;  but  in  so  far  as  no 
one  of  them  has  prevailed  over  the  others,  we  cannot  be  sure  there 
is  a  good  one  among  them. 

Sir  William  Ramsay  has  striven  to  show  that  radium  is  in  process 
of  transformation,  that  it  contains  a  store  of  energy  enormous  but 
not  inexhaustible. 

The  transformation  of  radium,  then,  would  produce  a  million 
times  more  of  heat  than  all  known  transformations;   radium  would 


PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICAL   PHYSICS        617 

wear  itself  out  in  1250  years;  you  see  that  we  are  at  least  certain 
to  be  settled  on  this  point  some  hundreds  of  years  from  now.  While 
waiting  our  doubts  remain. 

In  the  midst  of  so  many  ruins  what  remains  standing?  The  prin- 
ciple of  least  action  has  hitherto  remained  intact,  and  Larmor  appears 
to  believe  that  it  will  long  survive  the  others;  in  reality,  it  is  still 
more  vague  and  more  general. 

In  presence  of  this  general  ruin  of  the  principles,  what  attitude 
will  mathematical  physics  take? 

And  first,  before  too  much  perplexity,  it  is  proper  to  ask  if  all  this 
is  really  true.  All  these  apparent  contradictions  to  the  principles  are 
encountered  only  among  infinitesimals;  the  microscope  is  necessary 
to  see  the  Brownian  movement;  electrons  are  very  light;  radium  is 
very  rare,  and  no  one  has  ever  seen  more  than  some  milligrams  of 
it  at  a  time. 

And,  then,  it  may  be  asked  if,  beside  the  infinitesimal  seen,  there 
be  not  another  infinitesimal  unseen  counterpoise  to  the  first. 

So,  there  is  an  interlocutory  question,  and,  as  it  seems,  only 
experiment  can  solve  it.  We  have,  therefore,  only  to  hand  over  the 
matter  to  the  experimenters,  and,  while  waiting  for  them  to  deter- 
mine the  question  finally,  not  to  preoccupy  ourselves  with  these  dis- 
quieting problems,  but  quietly  continue  our  work,  as  if  the  princi- 
ples were  still  uncontested.  We  have  much  to  do  without  leaving 
the  domain  where  they  may  be  applied  in  all  security;  we  have 
enough  to  employ  our  activity  during  this  period  of  doubts. 

And  as  to  these  doubts,  is  it  indeed  true  that  we  can  do  nothing 
to  disembarrass  science  of  them?  It  may  be  said,  it  is  not  alone 
experimental  physics  that  has  given  birth  to  them;  mathematical 
physics  has  well  contributed.  It  is  the  experimenters  who  have  seen 
radium  throw  out  energy,  but  it  is  the  theorists  who  have  put  in 
evidence  all  the  difficulties  raised  by  the  propagation  of  light  across 
a  medium  in  motion;  but  for  these  it  is  probable  we  should  not  have 
become  conscious  of  them.  Well,  then,  if  they  have  done  their  best 
to  put  us  into  this  embarrassment,  it  is  proper  also  that  they  help  us 
to  get  out  of  it. 

They  must  subject  to  critical  examination  all  these  new  views 
I  have  just  outlined  before  you,  and  abandon  the  principles  only 
after  having  made  a  loyal  effort  to  save  them. 

What  can  they  do  in  this  sense?  That  is  what  I  will  try  to  ex- 
plain. 

Among  the  most  interesting  problems  of  mathematical  physics, 
it  is  proper  to  give  a  special  place  to  those  relating  to  the  kinetic 
theory  of  gases.  Much  has  already  been  done  in  this  direction,  but 
much  still  remains  to  be  done.  This  theory  is  an  eternal  paradox. 
We  have  reversibility  in  the  premises  and  irreversibility  in  the  con- 


618  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

elusions;  and  between  the  two  an  abyss.  Statistic  considerations, 
the  law  of  great  numbers,  do  they  suffice  to  fill  it?  Many  points 
still  remain  obscure  to  which  it  is  necessary  to  return,  and  doubtless 
many  times.  In  clearing  them  up,  we  shall  understand  better  the 
sense  of  the  principle  of  Carnot  and  its  place  in  the  ensemble  of 
dynamics,  and  we  shall  be  better  armed  to  interpret  properly  the 
curious  experiment  of  Gouy,  of  which  I  spoke  above. 

Should  we  not  also  endeavor  to  obtain  a  more  satisfactory  theory 
of  the  electro-dynamics  of  bodies  in  motion?  It  is  there  especially, 
as  I  have  sufficiently  shown  above,  that  difficulties  accumulate. 
Evidently  we  must  heap  up  hypotheses,  we  cannot  satisfy  all  the 
principles  at  once;  heretofore,  one  has  succeeded  in  safeguarding 
some  only  on  condition  of  sacrificing  the  others;  but  all  hope  of 
obtaining  better  results  is  not  yet  lost.  Let  us  take,  therefore,  the 
theory  of  Lorentz,  turn  it  in  all  senses,  modify  it  little  by  little,  and 
perhaps  everything  will  arrange  itself. 

Thus  in  place  of  supposing  that  bodies  in  motion  undergo  a  con- 
traction in  the  sense  of  the  motion,  and  that  this  contraction  is  the 
same  whatever  be  the  nature  of  these  bodies  and  the  forces  to  which 
they  are  otherwise  submitted,  could  we  not  make  an  hypothesis 
more  simple  and  more  natural? 

We  might  imagine,  for  example,  that  it  is  the  ether  which  is 
modified  when  it  is  in  relative  motion  in  reference  to  the  material 
medium  which  it  penetrates,  that  when  it  is  thus  modified,  it  no 
longer  transmits  perturbations  with  the  same  velocity  in  every  direc- 
tion. It  might  transmit  more  rapidly  those  which  are  propagated 
parallel  to  the  medium,  whether  in  the  same  sense  or  in  the  opposite 
sense,  and  less  rapidly  those  which  are  propagated  perpendicularly. 
The  wave  surfaces  would  no  longer  be  spheres,  but  ellipsoids,  and  we 
could  dispense  with  that  extraordinary  contraction  of  all  bodies. 

I  cite  that  only  as  an  example,  since  the  modifications  one  niight 
essay  would  be  evidently  susceptible  of  infinite  variation. 

It  is  possible  also  that  the  astronomer  may  some  day  furnish  us  data 
on  this  point;  he  it  was  in  the  main  who  raised  the  question  in 
making  us  acquainted  with  the  phenomenon  of  the  aberration  of  light. 
If  we  make  crudely  the  theory  of  aberration,  we  reach  a  very  curious 
result.  The  apparent  positions  of  the  stars  differ  from  their  real 
positions  because  of  the  motion  of  the  earth,  and  as  this  motion  is 
variable,  these  apparent  positions  vary.  The  real  position  we  cannot 
know,  but  we  can  observe  the  variations  of  the  apparent  position. 
The  observations  of  the  aberration  show  us,  therefore,  not  the 
movement  of  the  earth,  but  the  variations  of  this  movement;  they 
cannot,  therefore,  give  us  information  about  the  absolute  motion 
of  the  earth.  At  least  this  is  true  in  first  approximation,  but  it 
would  be  no  longer  the  same  if  we  could  appreciate  the  thousandths 


PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICAL  PHYSICS       619 

of  a  second.  Then  it  would  be  seen  that  the  amplitude  of  the  oscil- 
lation depends  not  alone  on  the  variation  of  the  motion,  variation 
which  is  well  known,  since  it  is  the  motion  of  our  globe  on  its  elliptic 
orbit,  but  on  the  mean  value  of  this  motion;  so  that  the  constant  of 
aberration  would  not  be  altogether  the  same  for  all  the  stars,  and  the 
differences  would  tell  us  the  absolute  motion  of  the  earth  in  space. 

This,  then,  would  be,  under  another  form,  the  ruin  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  relativity.  We  are  far,  it  is  true,  from  appreciating  the 
thousandths  of  a  second,  but  after  all,  say  some,  the  total  absolute 
velocity  of  the  earth  may  be  much  greater  than  its  relative  velocity 
with  respect  to  the  sun.  If,  for  example,  it  were  300  kilometers  per 
second  in  place  of  30,  this  would  suffice  to  make  the  phenomena 
observable. 

I  believe  that  in  reasoning  thus  we  admit  a  too  simple  theory 
of  aberration.  Michelson  has  shown  hs,  I  have  told  you,  that  the 
physical  procedures  are  powerless  to  put  in  evidence  absolute  mo- 
tion; I  am  persuaded  that  the  same  will  be  true  of  the  astronomic 
procedures,  however  far  one  pushes  precision. 

However  that  may  be,  the  data  astronomy  will  furnish  us  in 
this  regard  will  some  day  be  precious  to  the  physicist.  While  wait- 
ing, I  believe  the  theorists,  recalling  the  experience  of  Michelson, 
may  anticipate  a  negative  result,  and  that  they  would  accomplish 
a  useful  work  in  constructing  a  theory  of  aberration  which  would 
explain  this  in  advance. 

But  let  us  come  back  to  the  earth.  There  also  we  may  aid  the 
experimenters.  We  can,  for  example,  prepare  the  ground  by  study- 
ing profoundly  the  dynamics  of  electrons;  not,  be  it  understood, 
in  starting  from  a  single  hypothesis,  but  in  multiplying  hypotheses 
as  much  as  possible.  It  will  be,  then,  for  the  physicists  to  utilize 
our  work  in  seeking  the  crucial  experiment  to  decide  between  these 
different  hypotheses. 

This  dynamics  of  electrons  can  be  approached  from  many  sides, 
but  among  the  ways  leading  thither  is  one  which  has  been  somewhat 
neglected,  and  yet  this  is  one  of  those  which  promise  us  most  of  sur- 
prises. It  is  the  movements  of  the  electrons  which  produce  the  line 
of  the  emission  spectra;  this  is  proved  by  the  phenomenon  of  Zee- 
mann;  in  an  incandescent  body,  what  vibrates  is  sensitive  to  the 
magnet,  therefore  electrified.  This  is  a  very  important  first  point, 
but  no  one  has  gone  farther;  why  are  the  lines  of  the  spectrum 
distributed  in  accordance  with  a  regular  law? 

These  laws  have  been  studied  by  the  experimenters  in  their  least 
details;  they  are  very  precise  and  relatively  simple.  The  first  study 
of  these  distributions  recalled  the  harmonics  encountered  in  acous- 
tics; but  the  difference  is  great.  Not  only  the  numbers  of  vibrations 
are  not   the  successive  multiples  of  one  number,  but  we  do  not 


620  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

even  find  anything  analogous  to  the  roots  of  those  transcendental 
equations  to  which  so  many  problems  of  mathematical  physics  con- 
duct us:  that  of  the  vibrations  of  an  elastic  body  of  any  form,  that 
of  the  Hertzian  oscillations  in  a  generator  of  any  form,  the  problem 
of  Fourier  for  the  coohng  of  a  solid  body. 

The  laws  are  simpler,  but  they  are  of  whoUy  other  nature,  and  to 
cite  only  one  of  these  differences,  for  the  harmonics  of  high  order 
the  number  of  vibrations  tends  toward  a  finite  Umit,  instead  of 
increasing  indefinitely. 

That  has  not  yet  been  accounted  for,  and  I  believe  that  there  we 
have  one  of  the  most  important  secrets  of  nature.  Lindemann  has 
made  a  praiseworthy  attempt,  but,  to  my  mind,  without  success; 
this  attempt  should  be  renewed.  Thus  we  shall  penetrate,  so  to  say, 
into  the  inmost  recess  of  matter.  And  from  the  particular  point  of 
\'iew  which  we  to-day  occupy,  when  we  know  why  the  vibrations 
of  incandescent  bodies  differ  from  ordinary  elastic  vibrations,  w^hy 
the  electrons  do  not  behave  themselves  like  the  matter  which  is  familiar 
to  us.  we  shall  better  comprehend  the  dynamics  of  electrons  and 
it  will  be  perhaps  more  easy  for  us  to  reconcile  it  with  the  princi- 
ples. 

Suppose,  now,  that  all  these  efforts  fail,  and  after  all  I  do  not 
beheve  they  wiU,  what  must  be  done?  Will  it  be  necessary  to  seek 
to  mend  the  broken  principles  in  giving  what  we  French  call  a  coup 
de  pouce  9  That  is  evidently  always  possible,  and  I  retract  nothing 
I  have  formerly  said. 

Have  you  not  written,  you  might  say  if  you  wished  to  seek  a 
quarrel  with  me,  have  you  not  written  that  the  principles,  though  of 
experimental  origin,  are  now  unassailable  by  experiment  because 
they  have  become  conventions?  And  now  you  have  just  told  us  the 
most  recent  conquests  of  experiment  put  these  principles  in  danger. 
Well,  formerly  I  was  right  and  to-day  I  am  not  wrong. 

Formerly  I  was  right,  and  what  is  now  happening  is  a  new  proof 
of  it.  Take,  for  example,  the  calorimeter  experiment  of  Curie  on 
radium.  Is  it  possible  to  reconcile  that  with  the  principle  of  the 
conservation  of  energy? 

It  has  been  attempted  in  many  ways;  but  there  is  among  them 
one  I  should  like  you  to  notice. 

It  has  been  conjectured  that  radium  was  only  an  intermediary, 
that  it  only  stored  radiations  of  unknown  nature  which  flashed 
through  space  in  every  direction,  traversing  aU  bodies,  save  radium, 
without  being  altered  by  this  passage  and  without  exercising  any 
action  upon  them.  Radium  alone  took  from  them  a  little  of  their 
energy  and  afterward  gave  it  out  to  us  in  divers  forms. 

What  an  advantageous  explanation,  and  how  convenient!  First, 
it  is  unverifiable  and  thus  irrefutable.    Then  again  it  will  serve  to 


PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICAL   PHYSICS        621 

account  for  any  derogation  whatever  to  the  principle  of  Mayer;  it 
responds  in  advance  not  only  to  the  objection  of  Curie,  but  to  all 
the  objections  that  future  experimenters  might  accumulate.  This 
new  and  unknown  energy  would  serve  for  everything.  This  is  just 
what  I  have  said,  and  we  are  thereby  shown  that  our  principle  is 
unassailable  by  experiment. 

And  after  all,  what  have  we  gained  by  this  cowp  de  pouce  ? 
The  principle  is  intact,  but  thenceforth  of  what  use  is  it? 
It  permitted  us  to  foresee  that  in  such  or  such  circumstance  we 
could  count  on  such  a  total  quantity  of  energy;  it  limited  us;  but 
now  where  there  is  put  at  our  disposition  this  indefinite  provision  of 
new  energy,  we  are  limited  by  nothing;  and  as  I  have  written  else- 
where, if  a  principle  ceases  to  be  fecund,  experiment,  without  con- 
tradicting it  directly,  will  be  likely  to  condemn  it. 

This,  therefore,  is  not  what  would  have  to  be  done,  it  would  be 
necessary  to  rebuild  anew. 

If  we  were  cornered  down  to  this  necessity,  we  should  moreover 
console  ourselves.  It  would  not  be  necessary  to  conclude  that  science 
can  weave  only  a  Penelope's  web,  that  it  can  build  only  ephemeral 
constructions,  which  it  is  soon  forced  to  demolish  from  top  to  bot- 
tom with  its  own  hands. 

As  I  have  said,  we  have  already  passed  through  a  like  crisis.  I 
have  shown  you  that  in  the  second  mathematical  physics,  that  of 
the  principles,  we  find  traces  of  the  first,  that  of  the  central  forces; 
it  will  be  just  the  same  if  we  must  learn  a  third. 

When  an  animal  exuviates,  and  breaks  its  too  narrow  carapace  to 
make  itself  a  fresh  one,  we  easily  recognize  under  the  new  envelope 
the  essential  traits  of  the  organism  which  have  existed. 

We  cannot  foresee  in  what  way  we  are  about  to  expand;  perhaps 
it  is  the  kinetic  theory  of  gases  which  is  about  to  undergo  develop- 
ment and  serve  as  model  to  the  others.  Then,  the  facts  which  first 
appeared  to  us  as  simple,  thereafter  will  be  merely  results  of  a  very 
great  number  of  elementary  facts  which  only  the  laws  of  chance 
make  cooperate  for  a  common  end.  Physical  law  will  then  take  an 
entirely  new  aspect;  it  will  no  longer  be  solely  a  differential  equation, 
it  will  take  the  character  of  a  statistical  law. 

Perhaps,  likewise,  we  should  construct  a  whole  new  mechanics, 
of  which  we  only  succeed  in  catching  a  glimpse,  where  inertia  increas- 
ing with  the  velocity,  the  velocity  of  light  would  become  an  impass- 
able limit. 

The  ordinary  mechanics,  more  simple,  would  remain  a  first  approx- 
imation, since  it  would  be  true  for  velocities  not  too  great,  so  that  we 
should  still  find  the  old  dynamics  under  the  new. 

We  should  not  have  to  regret  having  believed  in  the  principles, 
and  even,  since  velocities  too  great  for  the  old  formulas  would  always 


622  APPLIED   MATHEMATICS 

be  only  exceptional,  the  surest  way  in  practice  would  be  still  to  act 
as  if  we  continued  to  believe  in  them.  They  are  so  useful,  it  would  be 
:necessary  to  keep  a  place  for  them.  To  determine  to  exclude  them 
altogether  would  be  todepriveone'sself  of  a  precious  weapon.  I  hasten 
to  say  in  conclusion  we  are  not  yet  there,  and  as  yet  nothing  proves 
that  the  principles  will  not  come  forth  from  the  combat  victorious 
and  intact. 


SHORT    PAPERS 


Three  short  papers  were  read  in  the  Section  of  Applied  Mathematics,  the  first 
by  Professor  Henry  T.  Eddy,  of  the  University  of  Minnesota,  on  "  The  Electro- 
magnetic Theory  and  the  Velocity  of  Light." 

The  second  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  Alexander  Macfarlane,  of  Chat- 
ham, Ontario,  "On  the  Exponential  Notation  in  Vector-analysis." 

The  third  paper  was  presented  by  Professor  James  McMahon,  of  Cornell  Uni- 
versity, "  On  the  Use  of  N-fold  Riemann  Spaces  in  Applied  Mathematics." 


WORKS   OF   REFERENCE 

(prepared    through    the    eOURTESY    OF   PROFESSOR   GEORGE    BRUCE    HAI-STED, 
OP  KENTON  COLLEGE,  AND  PROFESSOR  LUDWIG  BOLTZMAJSTN,  OP  THE  UNIVERSITY 

OP  Vienna) 

Allman,  G.  J.,  Greek  Geometry  from  Thales  to  Euclid.  Dublin,  Hodges,  1889. 
BuRNSiDE,  W.  S.,  Theory  of  Groups.    Cambridge  University  Press,  1897. 
Cajori,  F.,  The  Modem  Theory  of  Equations.  New  York,  The  Macmillan  Co., 
1904. 
The    Teaching    and    History  of    Mathematics    in    the    United    States. 

Washington,  1890,  Bureau  of  Education. 
A  History  of  Elementary  Mathematics.    New  York,  1896,  MacmiUan. 
Cantor,  Von  M.,  Vorlesungen  iiber  Geschichte  der  Mathematik.  In  3  Banden. 

Leipzig,  Teubner,  1894-1901. 
Cakhart,  D.,  Surveying.    Boston,  1888,  Giim  &  Co. 
Carr,  G.  S.,  S3mopsis  of  Elementary  Results  in  Pure  Mathematics.     London^ 

1886,  Hodgson. 
Chrtstal,  G.,  Algebra,  2  ed.  2  vols.  London,  1900,  Black. 
Cox,  HoMERSHAM,  Principles  of  Arithmetic,    Cambridge,  1885,  Deighton. 
Darboux,  Gaston,  Lecons  sur  les  Systemes  Orthogonaux  et  les  coordonnees- 
curvilignes.    Paris,  1898,  Gauthier-Villars. 
Lecons  sur  la  Theorie  Generale  des  Surfaces  et  les  Applications  G6o- 
metrique  du  Calcul  Infinitesimal.    4  vols.  1887-1896.    Paris,  Gau- 
thier-Villars. 
Frost,  P.,  Treatise  on  Curve  Tracing.    London,  1872,  Macmillan. 
Gibson,  G.  A.,  An  Introduction  to  the  Calculus  Based  on  Graphic  Methods. 

London,  1904,  Macmillan. 
Hagen,  J.  G.,  Synopsis  der  Hoheren  Mathematik.  Berlin,  1891-1901,  Dames. 
Halsted,  G.  B.,  Projective  Geometry.    New  York,  Wiley  &  Sons,  1905. 

Lobachevski's  Geometrical  Researches  on  the  Theory  of  Parallels,. 

4  ed.  Gambler,  Ohio,  The  Neomon,  1905. 
Bolyai's  Science  Absolute  of  Space.    Gambler,  Ohio,  The  Neomon,. 

1905. 
The  Elements  of  Geometry.    6  ed.  New  York,  Wiley  &  Sons,  1903 
Rational  Geometry.    New  York,  Wiley  &  Sons,  1904. 
Mensuration.   4  ed.  Boston,  Ginn  &  Co.,  1903. 

Synthetic  Geometry.    The  Lemoine-Brocard  Geometry.    3  ed.  New 
York,  1899,  Wiley  &  Sons. 
Harkness  and  Morley,  Introduction  to  the  Theory  of  Analytic  Functions, 

London,  1898,  Macmillan. 
Hilbert,  D.,  Grundlagen  der  Geometric.   2  ed.  Leipzig,  1903,  Teubner. 
Jessop,  C.  M.,  a  Treatise  on  the  Line  Complex.    Cambridge  University  Press, 

1903. 
Jordan,  M.  Camillb,  Cours  d' Analyse  de  I'Ecole  Poly  technique.  2  ed.  3  vols, 

Paris,  1903,  Gauthier-Villars. 
Langley,  E.  M.,  Computation.    London,  1895,  Longmans. 
Levett  and  Davidson,  Plane  Trigonometry.    London,  Macmillan,  1892. 
Love,  A.  E.  H.,  Theoretical  Mechanics.    Cambridge  University  Press,  1897. 
Mach,  E.,  The  Science  of  Mechanics,  a  critical  and  historical  account  of  its 
development.   Translated  by  T.  J.  McCormack.  2  ed.  Chicago, 1902,  The  Open 
Court  Pub.  Co. 


624  BIBLIOGRAPHY 

Mellor,  J.  W.,  Higher  Mathematics  for  Students  of  Chemistry  and  Physics. 

London,  1902,  Longmans. 
Morgan,  R.  B.,  Elementary  Graphs.    London,  1903,  Blackie. 
Mueller,  Felix,  Vocabulaire  Mathematique,  Francais-Allemand  et  AUemand- 

Francais,  contenant  les  termes  technique  employes  dans  les  mathematiques 

pures  et  appliques.  Leipzig,  1900,  Teubner,  vi,  316. 
Emil  Picard  and  Georges  Simart,    Theorie    des    Fonctions    Algebriques    de 

deux  Variables  Independants.    Paris,  Gauthier-Villars. 
Picard,  Eaiil,  Traits  d' Analyse.    4  vols.   Tome  i,  2  ed.   1901.    Tome  ii,  1893. 

Tome  III,  1896.    Paris,  Gauthier-Villars. 
Poincare,  H.,  La  Valeur  de  la  Science.    Paris,  E.  Flammarion,  1905. 
La  Science  et  I'Hypothese.    Paris,  E.  Flammarion. 
Les  Methodes    Nouvelles  de   la  Mecanique  celeste.    3  vols.    Paris, 

Gauthier-Villars,  1893. 
Calcul  des  Probabilites.    Paris,  Carr6  et  Naud,  1896. 
Russell,  Bertrand,  The  Principles  of   Mathematics.    Cambridge  University 

Press,  1903. 
Salmon,  G.,  Analytic    Geometry  of   Three   Dimensions.    4   ed.  Dublin,   1882, 
Simpkins. 
Treatise  on  the  Higher  Plane  Curves.    3  ed.  Dublin,  1879,  Hodges. 
Treatise  on  the  Conic  Sections.   6  ed.  London,  1879,  Longmans. 
-Lessons  Introductory  to  the  Modern  Higher  Algebra.  4  ed.  Dublin, 
1885,  Simpkins. 
Scott,  R.  F.,  Theory  of  Determinants.  2  ed.      Revised  by  G.   B.  Mathews. 

Cambridge  University  Press,  1905. 
Simon,  Dr.  Max,  Euklid  und    die   sechs    Planimetrischen    Bucher.     Leipzig, 

Teubner,  1901. 
Todhunter,  a  History  of  the  Theory  of  Probability.  Cambridge,  1865,  Macmillan. 
Todhunter  and  Leathen,  Spherical  Trigonometry.    London,  Macmillan,  1901. 
Willson,  F.  N.,  Descriptive  Geometry  and  Mechanical  Drawing.    New  York, 

Macmillan,  1904. 
Whitehead,  A.  N.,  Universal  Algebra.    Cambridge  University  Press,  1898. 
Withers,  J.  W.,  Euchd's  Parallel  Postulate.    Chicago,  The  Open  Court  Pub. 

Co.,  1905. 
Whittaker,  E.  T.,  Modern  Analysis.    Cambridge  University  Press,  1902. 
WoLFFiNG,  Ernst,  Mathematische    Biicherschatz,    Systematische   Verzerchniss 

der  Wichtigsten  Deutschen  und  Aiislandischen  Lehrbiicher  und  Monographien 

des  19.  Jahrhunderts  auf  dem  Gebiete   der  Mathematischen  Wissenschaften. 

Leipzig,  Teubner,  1903. 
Index  Du  Repertoire  Bibliographique  des  Sciences  Mathematiques.   2  ed.  1898. 

Paris,  Gauthiers-Villars. 
Repertoriam  der  Hoheren  Mathematik.  i,  Theil:  Analysis,   ii,  Theil:  Geometric. 

Leipzig,  1902,  Teubner. 
Encylopedie  des  Sciences  Mathematiques  pures  et  appliques.    Edition  francaise, 

redig^e  et  pubhee  d'apres  I'edition  allemande  sous  la  direction  de  Jules  Molk. 

Paris,  Gauthier-Villars,  1904. 


SPECIAL  WORKS  OF  REFERENCE 

(accompanying   PARTICUIiARLT   PROFESSOR   BOLTZMANN'S  ADDRBSs) 

BoLTZMANN,  LuDWiG,  Studien  iiber  das  Gleichgewicht  der  leb.  Kraft  zwischen 

Bewegten  Materiellen  Punkten.  Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  ii,  58,  p.  517, 1868. 
Losung  eines  Mechanischen  Problems.   Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  ii,  58  p.  1035, 

1868. 
Uber  das  Warmegleichgewicht  zwischen  Mehratomigen  Gasmolekulen. 

Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  n,  63  p.  397, 1871. 
Einige  allgemeine  Satze  iiber  Warmegleichgewicht.    Wien,  Sitz.  Ber. 

II,  63,  p.  679,  1871. 
Weitere  Studien  iiber  das  Warmegleichgewicht  unter  Gasmal.    Wien, 

Sitz.  Ber,  ii,  66,  p.  275,  1872. 
Uber  das  Warmegleichgewicht  von  Gasen,  anf  welche  Aussere  Kraf  te 

wirken.    Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  ii,  72,  p.  427,  1875. 
Uber  die  Anfstellung  mid  Integration  der  Gelichmigen,  welche  die 

Molecularbewegung  in  Gasen  bestimmen.    Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  ii,  74, 

p.  503,  1876. 
Bemerkmigen  iiber  einige  Probleme  der  Mechanischen  Warmetheorie. 

Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  ii,  75,  p.  62,  1877. 
Uber  die  Natur  der  Gasmolekule.    Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  ii,  74,  p.  553, 

1876. 
Uber  die  Beiziehung  zwischen  dem  Hauptsatze  der  Mechanischen 

Warmetheorie  u.  der  Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung.    Wien,  Sitz. 

Ber.  II,  76,  October,  1877. 
Weitere  Bemerkungen  iiber  einige  Probleme  der  mechanischen  War- 
metheorie.   Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  ii,  78,  p.  7,  1878. 
Uber  das  Arbeitsquantum  welches  bei  chemischen  Verbindungem 

gewonnen  werden  kann.   Wien,  Sitz.  Ber.  ii,  88,  p.  861,  1883. 
Uber  die  Eigenschaften  monocyklischer  imd  anderer  damit  verwandter 

Systeme.    Joum.  f.  r.  u.  a.  Math.  100,  p.  201,  1885. 
Uber  die  Mechanischen  Analogieen  des  2,  Hauptsatzes  der  Therm©- 

dynamik.    Joum.  f.  r.  u.  d.  Math.  100,  p.  201,  1885. 
Uber   das  Maxwellsche  Vertheilungsgesetz    der  Geschwindigkeiteni. 

Wied.  Ann.  55,  p.  223,  1895. 
Uber  eine  Abhanlung  Zerme  las.  Wied.    Ann.  60,  p.  392,  1897;  SI, 

p.  773,  1896. 
Uber  die  Sogenannte  H-Curoe.    Math.  Ann.  50,  p.  325,  1898. 
Vorlesungen  iiber  Gastheorie,  i,  1896,  ii,  1898,  bei  Barth,  Leipzig, 

besonders  ii,  Abschn.  iii,  und  vii;  and  French  translation  appensdo 

in.  to  vol.  II. 
On  the  EquiUbrium  of  Vis  Viva.   Phil.  Mag.  v,  p.  153, 1893. 
Encyklopadie  der  Math.  Wissenschaften,  vol.  iv.    D.  Mechanik  der 

aus  zahlreichen  diskreten  TheUen  bestehenden  Systeme.  27  Eia>- 

greiben  der  Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechn.   Teubner,  1905. 
BuRBURT,  Samuel  H.  On  Jeans's  Theory  of  Gases.    Phil.  Mag.  vi,  5,  p.  134, 

6,  p.  529,  1903. 
On  the  Variation  of  Entropy  by  W.  Gibbs.  Phil.  Mag.  vi,  6,  p..  251, 

1903. 
Cf.  also  Phil.  Mag.  January,  1904,  October,  1890,  etc. 


626  SPECIAL  BIBLIOGRAPHY 

CuLVERWELii,  Edward  P.,  Lord  Kelvin's  Test  Case  on  the  Maxwell-Boltzmann 

Law.   Nat.  46,  p.  76,  1892. 
GiBBS,  WiLLAKD,  Elementary  Principles  of  Statistical  Mechanics.    Scribner  Sons, 

1903. 
Jeans,  J.  H.,  The  Kinetic  Theory  of  Gases  Developed  from  a  New  Standpoint. 
PhU.  Mag.  VI,  5,  p.  597,  6,  p.  720,  1903. 
On  the  Vibrations  set  up  in  Molecules  by  Collisions.    Phil.  Mag.  vi, 

6,  p.  279,  1903. 
The  Dynamic  Theory  of  Gases,  Cambridge  University  Press,  1904. 
LiENARD,  Notes  sur  la  Th^orie  Cinetique  des  gaz.    Joum.  de  Physique,  iv,  2,  p. 

677,  1903. 
Maxwell,  James  CilAJRK,  Illustrations   of   the   Dynamical   Theory   of   Gases. 
Phil.  Mag.  IV,  19,  p.  19,  1860;  20,  p.  21,  1860. 
Scientific  Paper,  i,  p.  379. 
Dynamical  Theory  of  Gases.    Phil.  Mag.  rv,  ser.  vol.  35,  p.  729;  Scient. 

pap.  II,  p.  26. 
On  Boltzmann's  Theorem.    Cambr.  Phil.  Trans.  12,  part  3,  p.  547, 

1879;  Scient.  pap.  ii,  713. 
On  Stresses  in  Rarefied  Gases.    Phil.  Trans.  Roy.  Soc.  1879,  i,  p.  231; 
Scient.  pap.  ii,  p.  681. 
Ratleigh,  Lord,  On  Maxwell's  Investigations  respecting  Boltzmann's  Theorem. 
Phil.  Mag.  V,  33,  p.  356,  1892. 
Dynamical  Problems  in  Illustration  of  the  Theory  of  Gases.    Phil. 

Mag.  V,  32,  p.  424,  1891. 
The  Law  of  Partition  of  Kinetic  Energy.    Phil.  Mag.  v,  49,  p.  98, 
1900. 
Waals,  Jun.  Van  der.  Die  statistische  Naturanschauung.    Rieckes  Physikal. 

Zeitschrift  4.,  p.  508,  1903. 
Zermelo,  Uber  die  Mechanische  Erklarung  irreversibler  Vorgange.  Wied.  Ann. 
57,  p.  485;  59,  p.  793,  1896.    Cf.  also  Poincar^'s  Thermodynamique. 


CONTENTS  OF  THE  SERIES 

Volume  I.  History  of  the  Congress;  The  Scientific  Plan  of  the  Congress;  Intro- 
ductory Address;  Department  of  Philosophy  (6  sections);  Department 
of  Mathematics  (3.  sections). 

Volume  II.  Department  of  Political  and  Economic  History  (6  sections);  De- 
partment of  History  of  Law  (3  sections) ;  Department  of  History  of  Religion 
(5  sections). 

Volume  III.  Department  of  History  of  Language  (8  sections);  Department  of 
History  of  Literature  (7  sections) ;  Department  of  History  of  Art  (3  sections.) 

Volume  IV.  Department  of  Physics  (3  sections);  Department  of  Chemistry 
(4  sections);  Department  of  Astronomy  (2  sections);  Department  of 
Sciences  of  the  Earth  (8  sections). 

Volume  V.  Department  of  Biology  (11  sections);  Department  of  Anthropolog}^ 
(3  sections) ;  Department  of  Psychology  (4  sections) ;  Department  of  Socio- 
logy (2  sections).  , 

Volume  VI.  Department  of  Medicine  (12  sections) ;  Department  of  Technology' 
(6  sections). 

Volume  VII.  Department  of  Economics  (6  sections) ;  Department  of  Politics 
(5  sections);  Department  of  Jurisprudence  (3  sections);  Department  of 
Social  Science  (6  sections). 

Volume  VIII.  Department  of  Education  (5  sections) ;  Department  of  Religion 
(6  sections). 


PRINTED  BY  H.  O.  HOUGHTON  &  CO. 

CAMBRIDGE,  MASS. 

U.S.  A.