Skip to main content

Full text of "An introduction to the science of thought"

See other formats


/ 


THE 

"  CIENCE 

OF 


s 


THOUGHT 


AN   INTRODUCTION 


TO  THE 


SCIENCE  OF  THOUGHT. 


3 


g  S^V^HEBBERD. 


3 

MADISON, 


wis. : 


TRACY,   GIBBS   &    CO.,    PUBLISHERS. 
1892. 


h» 


■Fter* 


*%■«>■* 


THE  LIBRARY 
OF  CONGRESS 

WAIHINOTOW 


l8Q2. 

Copyrighted  by  S.  S.  HEBBERD. 


V 


PREFACE. 


Knowing  how  little  interest  the  present  age  takes 
in  philosophy,  I  have  compressed  this  book  *into  the 
smallest  possible  compass.  What  might  well  have 
been  expanded  into  a  volume,  I  have  condensed  into 
a  chapter,  and  often  into  a  page.  I  shall  probably  be 
accused,  upon  this  very  account,  of  a  slight  and  pre- 
sumptuous treatment  of  great  themes.  It  is  right, 
therefore,  for  me  to  add  in  self  defense  that  I  have 
spent  a  quarter  of  a  century  in  the  discovery  and 
demonstration  of  what  is  here  presented  in  less  than 
a  hundred  pages. 

S.  S.  Hebberd. 

Viroqua,    Wis.,  Aug.  12,  iSp2. 


CONTENTS. 


Chapter        I.  Self-Consciousness. 

II.  Perception. 

III.  Space. 

IV.  Concepts. 
V.  Science. 

VI.  Morality. 

VII.  Art. 

VIII.  Pagan  Civilization. 

IX.  Christian  Civilization. 


SCIENCE  OF  THOUGHT. 


CHAPTER    I. 
SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. 

All  thinking  is  a  relating  of  cause  and  effect. 
The  present  treatise  is  designed  to  demonstrate  this 
simple  principle  —  to  show  that  every  perfect  thought, 
from  the  simplest  to  the  most  complex,  contains  two 
elements  related  to  each  other  as  cause  and  effect; 
and  that  whenever  either  of  these  elements  is  sup- 
pressed, thought  thereby  becomes  vague,  one-sided, 
fatally  defective.  In  this  synthesis,  the  very  nature 
of  thought  consists. 

But  although  this  principle  is  so  simple,  it  will  be 
found  to  be  of  immeasurable  value.  It  will  put  an 
end  to  the  chief  disputes  which  have  heretofore  di- 
vided and  distracted  human  speculation;  it  will  furnish 
a  basis  for  true  theories  of  science,  morality  and  art; 
it  will  explain  the  course  of  human  civilization  and  so 
provide  a  genuine  philosophy  of  history. 

To  verify  our  principle  we  must  begin  with  self-con- 
sciousness, the  most  immediate  and  universal  of  all 
forms  of  thinking. 

Seeking  an  unassailable  definition  of  self-conscious- 
ness, I  affirm  it  to  be  the  immediate  knowledge  of  our 
mental  states  as  onr  own.      They  are  thought  of  as  our 


8 


SCIENCE    01     l  BOUGHT. 


own,  not  only  in  the  sense  of  mere  possession   but  of 

active  control;  up  to  a  certain  point  they  come  at  our 
call  and  go  at  our  bidding;  we  are,  partially  at  least, 
their  producing  and  controlling  cause.  It  is  this  im- 
mediate reference  of  mental  states  to  self  as  their 
cause,  which  forms  the  very  essence  of  self -conscious- 
ness, distinguishing  it  from  all  other  kinds  of  activity, 
mental  or  physical.  And  in  this  process  are  manifestly 
the  two  factors  which  our  law  demands.  Self-con- 
sciousness is  the  relating  of  self  to  mental  states  as 
the  one,  permanent  cause  of   many,  transitory  effects. 

It  follows,  therefore,  from  our  principle,  that  nei- 
ther of  these  two  elements  which  together  form  the 
conception  of  self-consciousness,  can  be  fully  thought 
or  known  apart  from  the  other.  The  cause  can  be 
known  only  in  and  through  its  effects;  and  conversely, 
the  effect  only  in  and  through  its  cause.  Self  in  itself, 
a  mental  state  in  itself,  each  of  these  is  but  a  half- 
thought,  vague,  mutilated,  unintelligible.  Every  the- 
ory of  self-consciousness  which  attempts  to  suppress 
either  of  the  two  elements  must  end  in  incoherent  and 
divisive  thought.  This  deduction  is  wonderfully  ver- 
ified by  the  history  of  speculation,  as  we  shall  show 
by  two  leading  instances. 

(i).  Hume's  famous  formula  thatthere  isno  conscious- 
ness save  of  a  series  of  mental  states,  attempts  to 
eliminate  the  causal  element.  But  his  statement,  in 
the  effort  to  expunge  the  conception  of  self,  has  taken 
all  meaning  out  of  the  conception  of  conscious  states. 
For,  firstly,  it  ignores  memory,  the  very  core  of  con- 
sciousness— the  power  present  in    every    mental   state 


SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS.  9 

of  reproducing  the  past;  secondly,  in  suppressing  the 
sense  of  identity,  it  takes  away  all  that  can  distin- 
guish a  conscious  from  an  unconscious  state;  thirdly, 
it  is  in  the  last  resort  an  altogether  unintelligible  state- 
ment— to  speak  of  a  disconnected  series  as  aware  of 
itself  as  a  series,  is  to  utter  a  combination  of  sounds 
without  a  shred  of  meaning. 

But  why  waste  time  in  arguing  against  a  definition 
of  conscious  states  which  even  its  author  has  confessed 
to  be  unintelligible  ?  "All  my  hopes  vanish,"  Hume 
said,  "when  I  come  to  explain  the  principles  which 
unite  our  successive  perceptions  in  ourconsciousness." 
J.  S.  Mill,  although  adopting  the  same  view,  goes 
even  further  and  admits  that  the  theory  "involves  a 
paradox;"  that  "it  cannot  be  expressed  in  any  terms 
which  do  not  deny  its  truth."  He  does,  indeed,  at- 
tempt to  qualify  this  confession  by  adding  that  self- 
consciousness  is  an  ultimate  fact  and  therefore  inex- 
plicable, but  even  if  a  fact  is  ultimate  and  inexplic- 
able, it  by  no  means  follows  that  the  statement  of 
the  fact  must  be  unintelligible.  By  no  such  salvo  can 
Mill  break  the  force  of  his  admission  that  any  exposi- 
tion of  conscious  states  which  does  not  refer  them  to 
self  as  their  cause,  is  so  utterly  unintelligible  that  it 
cannot  even  be  expressed  in  any  terms  which  do  not 
deny  its  truth.  Effects  cannot  be  known  except  in  and 
through  their  cause. 

(2).  Kant's  exposition,  on  the  other  hand,  wonder- 
fully confirms  the  second  part  of  our  law,  that  in  re- 
gard to  the  knowledge  of  causes.  He  affirms,  in  a 
somewhat  bewildered  way,  the  unity  of  self-conscious- 


io  scn.v  !■;   oi-    Tiiorcii  r. 

ness.  But  he  hastens  to  add  that  this  unity  is  purely 
"logical,"  or  "formal,"  that  "the  notion  of  self  is  an 
altogether  empty  one."     And  to  prove  this,  he  argues 

long  and  laboriously  that  self  cannot  be  conceived  as 
substance.  Hut  when  he  has  established  this  point, 
he  has  done-  nothing  but  confirm  our  law  that  a  cause 
cannot  be  known  in  itself,  but  only  in  and  through  its 
effects.  A  substance  can  be  known  not  in  itself, 
but  only  through  the  sensuous  attribute  or  effects 
which  it  produces.  .And  similarly,  self  can  be  known 
only  in  and  through  its  effects — through  that  vast  and 
varied  host  of  mental  states  which  it  creates  or  con- 
trols. It  is  in  vain,  therefore,  that  any  one  at- 
tempts to  define  self  in  terms  of  substance,  or  in  any 
other  way,  except  as  the  one  permanent  cause  of  our 
many  transient,  mental  states. 

Our  law  is  verified  in  both  its  parts  so  far  as  self- 
conciousness  is  concerned.  It  is  necessary,  however, 
to  lay  the  chief  stress  on  that  part  which  relates  to 
the  knowledge  of  effects.  Ever  since  the  days  of 
Kant,  thinkers  have  found  it  easy  to  perceive  that  a 
cause  in  itself — self,  substance  or  thing — is  unknowable. 
Hut  they  have  not  been  taught  to  perceive  also  that 
effects  in  themselves — conscious  states,  sensuous  attri- 
butes or  phenomena — are  equally  unknowable.  The 
future  of  philosophy  depends  upon  the  clear  recogni- 
tion of  the  fact  that  no  complete  thought  or  real  knowl- 
edge is  possible  unless  both  elements — the  cause  and 
the  effect — are  combined  in  that  synthesis  which  the 
nature  of  thinking  demands. 


CHAPTER  II. 
PERCEPTION. 

Philosophy  in  its  search  after  a  true  theory  of  per- 
ception has  been  driven  to  a  strange  pass.  The  most 
universal  and  unconquerable  conviction  of  mankind — 
the  belief  in  the  reality  of  an  external  world — proves 
to  be  the  very  one  which  most  completely  defies  phil- 
osophic explanation.  Speculation  has  finally  split  in- 
to two  schools,  the  one  regarding  the  belief  in  external 
reality  as  a  mere  illusion,  the  other  regarding  it  as  an 
utter  mystery,  an  inexplicable  intuition  or  instinct 
coming  no  one  knows  whence  or  how.  No  wonder 
that  philosophy  is   in  disgrace. 

But  surely  there  must  be  some  way  out  of  this 
wilderness  of  controversy  and  bewilderment;  and  we 
hope  to  show  that  there  is. 

Certain  of  our  mental  states  are,  mainly  at  least,  the 
products  of  our  own  activity;  we  imagine,  we  remember 
we  will  this  thing  or  that  as  we  please.  But  our  per- 
ceptive states  are  not  thus  self-produced;  we  are  con- 
scious that  they  are  given  to  us,  not  formed  by  us; 
there  is  a  regular  recurrence  of  the  parts  and  a  fixed 
order  of  the  whole  which  no  mental  effort  can  change. 
And  therefore  we  are  compelled  by  the  very  nature  of 
thought  to  ascribe  these  perceptive  states  to  some 
causality  not  our  own. 

This  conviction  of  an  external  causality  is  absolutely 
universal,  immediate   and    primordial.      It   is    not    an 


12  SCIENCE    OF   THOUCIIN. 

intuition-  one  of  those  instinctive  beliefs  or  innate- 
ideas  of  which  the  world  long  since  grew  weary.  It 
is  not  an  inference,  since  there  is  before  it,  no  prior 
judgment  from  which  it  lias  been  derived.  It  is  but 
a  restatement  of  the  fact  given  in  consciousness  that 
certain  states  are  not  produced  by  self;  and  the 
equivalence  of  the  two  statements  is  involved  in  the 
very  nature  of  thought.  It  lies  at  the  beginning  of 
consciousness;  it  is  enfolded  in  the  first  completed  act 
of  perception. 

Let  me  not  be  misunderstood.  Consciousness  in 
itself,  gives  us  nothing  beyond  this  fact  of  a  causality 
not  our  own.  What  that  causality  is — what  are  its 
defining  characteristics — cannot  be  thus  primordially 
and  infallibly  determined,  but  must  be  learned  through 
the  processes  of  the  understanding.  This  external 
source  of  perception  may  be  the  supreme  spirit  of  the 
Berkeleian  metaphysics;  it  maybe  the  famous  "Thing 
in  itself"  of  the  Kantian  philosophy;  it  may  be  that 
bright  world  of  living  reality  which  common  sense  is 
so  loath  to  give  up.  These  questions  pure  conscious- 
ness does  not  pretend  to  settle. 

It  may  seem  that  we  have  made  but  slight  progress 
towards  the  attainment  of  a  complete  theory  of  per- 
ception. But  at  least  we  have  put  an  end,  forever, 
to  subjective  idealism.  This  paradoxical  doctrine, 
under  whatsoever  elusive  forms  it  may  veil  itself,  is 
essentially  nothing  more  than  a  denial  of  all  external 
causality.  But  as  we  have  seen,  the  fact  of  a  causal- 
ity not  our  own,  is  immediately  and  universally  given 
us  in   self-consciousness;   and    therefore    it    cannot    be 


PERCEPTION.  13 

really  disbelieved  by  any  one.  Hence  subjective 
idealism  is  but  a  verbal  negation  of  what  no  one  can 
actually  doubt;  its  doctrine  cannot  be  fully  thought 
out  or  expressed  except  in  terms  which  deny  its 
truth.  All  the  subjective  idealists — like  Fichte  for 
instance,  with  his  "limitations  of  self-consciousness" — 
have  been  finally  compelled  to  assume  what  they 
were  attempting  to  contradict. 


To  recognize  that  external  causality  is  immediately 
given  us  in  consciousness — this  is  the  first  step  to- 
wards a  true  theory  of  knowledge.  The  second  step 
consists  in  clearing  away  the  difficulties  and  perplex- 
ities that  have  been  raised  by  objective  idealism. 
That  doctrine, — at  least  in  the  fully  developed  form 
given  it  by  Kant, — denies,  not  the  existence,  but  the 
knowableness  of  external  causality.  It  teaches  that 
substances,  things  in  themselves,  lie  beyond  the  limits 
of  human  knowledge.  We  can  know  only  phenomena, 
attributes,  the  effects  produced  by  the  unknowable 
cause  or  causes. 

We  can  gladly  accept  that  part  of  the  idealistic 
doctrine  which  affirms  the  unknowableness  of  sub- 
stance or  things  in  themselves;  for  that*is  but  an  an- 
ticipation of  our  own  fundamental  law.  A  cause  can 
be  known  only  in  or  through  its  effects.  Nothing  is 
more  utterly  unknowable  than  "pure  existence,"  a 
"thing  in  itself,"  a  substance  divested  of  all  its  at- 
tributes. 

But  idealism  has  been  utterly  blind  to  the  other 
half  of   this   fundamental   law;   it   has   not   seen   that 


14  SCIENCE   OF   THOUGH!  . 

effects  also  are  known  only  In  and  through  their 
causes.     While  insisting   that    substances    or    things 

in  themselves  are  unknowable-,  it  has  silently  claimed 
to  have  a  clear,  sun-lit  knowledge  of  effects — attri- 
butes, phenomena,  sensations  —  in  themselves.  Rut 
this,  as  I  shall  now  show,  is  an  amazing  illusion. 
So  far  as  there  can  be  any  difference  of  degree,  the 
sensation  or  effect  in  itself  is  even  more  inscrutable 
than  tlie  cause  in  itself. 

Firstly,  let  us  consider  sensations  in  their  general 
nature.  In  vision,  for  instance,  we  have  some  dim 
glimpses  of  a  process  of  causation  passing  from  the 
object  seen  to  the  mind.  Rut  this  causal  process 
ends  in  complete  mystery.  We  have  not  the  slight- 
est knowledge  of  the  effect  finally  produced  upon  the 
mind.  The  perfected  perception  has  no  character  of 
internality  or  ideality;  on  the  contrary,  the  vision  ap- 
pears to  be  entirely  external  and  spatial.  Somehow, 
the  cause  and  the  effect  have  come  to  be  inexplicably 
conjoined. 

•  Secondly,  consider  sensations  in  their  specific  char- 
acteristics. Do  we  know  aught  of  the  difference  be- 
tween them?  The  effect  produced  upon  the  mind  by 
a  round  object,  for  instance,  is  this  sensation  itself 
circular?  Is  the  sensation  of  sweetness  itself  sweet  ? 
Is  the  sensation  of  a  mountain  any  taller  than  the  sen- 
sation of  an  ant-hill?  In  a  word,  sensations  in  them- 
selves have  no  definable  characteristics;  they  are 
knowable  only  when  related  to  their  causes.  In  a 
complete   and    distinct   perception,    two   vague,  unin- 


PERCEPTION.  15 

telligible  half-ideas — the  one  of  a  producing  cause, 
the  other  of  its  effect — are  inseparably  combined. 

Thirdly,  consider  the  grouping  of  sensations.  Two 
or  more  sensations  are  brought  to  the  mind  through 
different  channels;  one,  for  instance,  through  the 
sense  of  sight,  another  through  that  of  touch.  Their 
union  in  one  perception  must  ever  remain  unintelli- 
gible, unless  we  conceive  of  them  as  different  effects 
of  a  common  cause  or  object. 

Fourthly,  the  same  fact  is  shown  in  the  recurrence 
of  sensations.  Every  sensation  carries  with  it  the  con- 
viction that  it  will  be  invariably  repeated  under  simi- 
lar circumstances;  and  this  characteristic  also  remains 
incomprehensible  except  we  regard  all  these  actual  or 
possible  sensations  as  the  many  transient  effects  of  one 
permanent  cause. 

It  has  been  proved,  then,  in  this  four-fold  way,  that 
we  have  just  as  little  knowledge  of  effects  or  phenom- 
ena in  themselves  as  we  have  of  causes  or  things  in 
themselves.  Thus  the  whole  ground  of  idealistic  ag- 
nosticism is  swept  away.  We  see  that  so  long  as  we 
disrupt  the  two  elements  of  thought  and  insist  upon 
regarding  either  apart  from  the  other,  we  can  have 
only  mystery,  confusion  and  unknowableness.  Knowl- 
edge begins  when  we  combine  substance  and  attribute, 
the  "thing  in  itself"  and  its  phenomena,  in  the  rela- 
tion of  cause  and  effect.  To  doubt  the  existence  of 
the  one  is  as  irrational  as  to  doubt  the  existence  of 
the  other. 


in  SCIEN(  I.    <  >I   THOUGHT. 

A  third  step  still  remains  before  reaching  a  com- 
plete theory  <>f  perceptive  knowledge.  The  question 
is  continually  asked:  How  do  we  know  that  our  per- 
ceptions correspond  with  external  reality?  The  qu 
tion  is  unanswerable;  and  that  for  the  simple  reason 
that  there  is  no  such  correspondence.  1'erccptive 
knowledge  does  not  consist  in  the  tracing  of  resem- 
blances between  objects  so  diverse  as  mental  states 
and  the  external  world. 

Perception,  on  the  contrary,  is  a  process  of  discrim- 
ination. Consciousness,  as  we  have  seen,  gives  to  us 
the  infallible  assurance  of  an  external  causality.  It  is 
the  province  of  perception  to  break  up  this  causality 
into  its  constituent  parts,  each  duly  related  to  its  ap- 
propriate effects. 

But  what  guarantee  have  we,  it  may  be  asked,  of 
the  accuracy  of  this  discriminating  process?  I  an- 
swer that  the  guarantee  is  five-fold.  First,  there  is 
the  uniform  recurrence  of  precisely  similar  perceptions, 
and  thereby  we  are  enabled  to  relate  them  to  the  same 
permanent  cause.  Secondly,  we  are  able  to  repeat 
perceptions  at  will,  and  thus  to  experiment,  as  it  were, 
upon  their  producing  causes.  Thirdly,  we  can  com- 
pare perceptions  received  through  one  organ  of  sense 
with  those  received  through  another — those  of  sight 
with  those  of  touch,  for  instance.  Fourthly,  and  most 
important  of  all,  we  soon  learn  to  discriminate  with 
ease  and  certainty,  between  our  own  bodies  and  the 
rest  of  the  external  world;  and  thus  are  provided  with 
an  instrument  and  an  unerring  test  of  all  subsequent 
discriminations.  Fifthly,  all  these  guarantees  may  be 
combined  so  a,s  to  strengthen  and  support  each    other. 


PERCEPTION.  17 

The  evidence  of  the  senses,  then,  is  strong  and 
overwhelming,  but  let  us  remember  that  it  is  not  in- 
fallible. Too  great  confidence  in  perception  has  ever 
been  one  of  the  chief  causes  of  human  ignorance.  And 
a  certain  idealistic  distrust  of  the  senses,  as  will  be 
shown  hereafter,  has  been  the  indispensable  prepara- 
tion for  that  scientific  research  which  changes  the  first 
crude  perceptions  of  mankind  into  a  more  exact  but 
still  defective  view  of  the  universe. 

Corollary  1.  A  certain  school  of  philosophy  declares 
perception  to  be  an  ultimate,  indecomposable  act  de- 
fying all  analysis.  But  we  have  now  analyzed  it.  And 
besides  upon  its  very  surface  perception  appears  as 
exceedingly  complex.  There  is  first  the  idea  of  a  per- 
ceiving self,  then  of  a  peculiar  mode  of  mental  activ- 
ity, then  of  an  object  perceived;  and  all  these  inter- 
acting in  an  endless  variety  of  subtile  implications. 
To  pronounce  all  this  complexity  to  be  simple  is  plain- 
ly the  last  refuge  of  distressed  philosophers. 

Corollary  2.  Sir  Wm  Hamilton  and  others  assert 
that  they  are  conscious  of  external  objects.  This 
amazing  doctrine  must  not  be  confounded  with  that 
of  these  pages.  I  have  taught  that  we  are  conscious 
of  a  certain  element  in  our  perceptive  states  as  not 
produced  by  self;  and  that,  therefore,  we  are  com- 
pelled— not  by  any  instinct  or  intuition,  but  by  the 
very  nature  of  thought — to  instantly  and  infallibly  as- 
cribe this  element  to  a  causality  not  our  own.  But 
that  is  very  different  from  teaching  that  we  are  con- 
scious of  stars,  or  sticks,  or  pictures  upon  the    retina. 


CHAPTER     III. 
SPACE. 

The  idea  of  space   has  long  been  one  ol  the  chief 

battle-grounds  of  philosophy.  By  one  party  it  has 
been  regarded  as  a  mere  mental  creation,  by  the 
other  as  the  idea  of  something  actually  existent;  and 
even  the  last  must  be  conscious  that  their  conception 
of  space  as  a  reality  is,  somehow,  exceedingly  vague 
and  elusive.  Let  us  see  now  what  light  our  principle 
can  throw  upon  this  darkened  field  of  debate. 

The  conception  of  space  is  evidently  compounded  of 
two  elements.  On  the  one  side  is  the  idea  of  pure 
space,  one,  continuous,  unchanging,  unlimited;  on  the 
other  we  have  the  idea  of  positions,  distances,  figures 
and  all  the  other  countless  spatial  relations. 

Furthermore,  these  two  elements  are  related  to 
each  other  as  cause  and  effect.  All  possible  spatial 
or  geometrical  relations  can  be  reduced  to  one  gen- 
eral formula;  each  of  them  is,  essentially,  a  separation 
of  points  or  things  by  space.  These  countless  separa- 
tions between  bodies  cannot  be  thought  of  or  made 
intelligible  save  as  resulting  from  the  existence  of 
one  continuous  and  infinite  space;  they  are  the  many, 
transient  effects  of   one  permanent  cause. 

But  it  will  instantly  be  objected  that  spatial  rela- 
tions are  not  effects,  but  merely  parts  of  space.  A 
figure,  it  will  be  said,  for  instance,  is  but  a  certain 
definite  part   of  space   cut  out  from  the  indefinite   re- 


SPACE.  19 

mainder.  But  the  objection  is  grounded  upon  a 
strange,  although  quite  universal  oversight.  It  is 
forgotten  that  space  can  really  have  no  parts;  we  are 
compelled  to  think  of  it  as  absolutely  continuous,  and, 
therefore,  indivisible.  If  space  could  be  separated 
into  two  or  more  parts,  what  would  separate  them  ? 
The  so-called  parts  of  space  are  pure  fictions,  invented 
by  the  mind  for  its  own  convenience  in  measuring 
bodies;  but,  while  using  these  fictions,  the  mind  is 
fully  aware  that  parts  of  space  cannot  really  exist. 
Therefore,  spatial  relations  cannot  be  clearly  and 
exactly  conceived  as  parts  of  a  whole,  but  only  as 
effects  of  a  cause.  Distances,  positions,  dimensions, 
directions  and  all  other  geometrical  properties  are  the 
many,  ever-changing  relations  established  between 
bodies  by  infinite,  continuous  and  unchanging  space. 
Once  again  then  our  doctrine  has  proved  impreg- 
nable. Every  spatial  conception  has  been  shown  to 
contain  two  elements.  And  only  thus  does  space — 
that  obscurest  and  most  perplexing  of  words — gain  a 
clear,  consistent  meaning. 


Is  space  then  actually  existent?  May  it  not  be, 
after  all,  a  mere  abstraction — an  ideal  phantasm 
which  floats  in  nothingness?  The  mind,  it  may  be 
said,  establishes  spatial  relations  between  bodies,  and 
if  the  bodies  cease  to  exist,  so  will  the  relations  be- 
tween them.  All  that  is  true  enough;  but  it  shoots 
far  and  wide  from  the  mark.  The  bodies  may  vanish 
and  with  them  their  spatial  relations.  But  the  space 
which   produced   that   relationship  will   remain  undis- 


20  SCIENi  i    l  >\     i  BOUGHT. 

turbed.  Two  stars  might  burn  themselves  out;  but 
the-  immensity  of  distance,  the  extent  of  space  which 
once  separated  them  would  not  be  changed  a  hair's- 
breadth.  And  if  the  whole  material  universe  should 
be  blotted  out,  infinite  space  would  still  remain,  one, 
continuous,  unchanging,  as  before.  In  fact  the  ol 
ion  serves  only  to  bring  out  vividly  our  view  of  spatial 
relations  as  the  many  transitory  effects  of  one  perma- 
nent cause. 

It  is  then  absolutely  impossible  to  think  of  space  as 
non-existent.  Let  us  understand  the  full  force  and 
sweep  of  this  declaration.  If  it  was  merely  some 
mental  instinct  or  "intuition"  or  Kantian  "form  of 
sense"  that  compelled  us  to  think  of  the  world  as  spa- 
tial, then  it  would  be  easy  enough  to  conceive  of  some 
higher  grade  of  mind  as  free  from  this  mysterious 
compulsion  imposed  upon  us;  and  so  it  would  be  very 
far  from  being  impossible  for  us  to  think  of  space  as 
non-existent.  But  we  have  shown  that  we  are  compel- 
led, not  by  any  intuition  or  form  of  sense,  but  by  the 
very  nature  of  thought,  to  conceive  of  space  as  a  cause 
of  all  spatial  relations.  And  to  think  away  whatever 
is  demanded  by  the  very  nature  of  thought,  is,  in  the 
fullest  sense  of  the  term,  absolutely  impossible;  not 
even  archangels  could  accomplish  that  feat. 


Any  thoughtful  reader  arrived  at  our  present  point 
of  view,  can  readily  meet  Kant's  proofs  of  the  ideality 
of  space.  But  it  may  be  well  to  briefly  notice  one  of 
these  alleged  proofs — the  geometrical  argument. 


SPACE.  2 1 

Experience,  Kant  urges,  concerns  only  the  con- 
tingent; it  can  therefore  never  give  the  universal  and 
necessary  judgments  of  geometry.  It  can  assure  us, 
for  instance,  that  two  lines  are  parallel  so  far  as  we 
have  examined  them,  but  not  that  they  would  con- 
tinue to  be  parallel  if  prolonged  through  infinite 
space.  Such  judgments  are  possible,  only  because 
space  is  not  objective — for  then  we  could  know  it  only 
contingently  through  experience  —  but  purely  subject- 
ive, a  merely  ideal  construction  imposed  upon  things 
by  the  mind. 

But  this,  besides  being  paradoxical,  explains  noth- 
ing. It  is  flat  tautology.  It  simply  asserts  that  that 
must  be  true  for  us  which  we  are  compelled  by  the 
mysterious  conformation  of  our  minds  to  think  as  true. 

From  our  present  point  of  view  the  real  explana- 
tion is  easily  found.  Pure  space  is  never  the  cause  of 
change;  on  the  contrary  it  is  the  cause  or  ground  of  the 
very  opposite  of  change — that  is,  of  separation  and  posi- 
tion or  relative  fixedness.  Therefore,  the  ideal  rela- 
tions of  pure  space,  with  which  geometry  deals,  are 
invariable;  and  that  for  the  simple  reason  that  by 
hypothesis  all  causes  of  change  arc  excluded.  Two 
parallel  lines  will  maintain  their  parallelism  through 
the  whole  infinitude  of  space,  unless  we  should  some- 
where mentally  change  the  direction  of  one  of  them 
and  so  make  three  lines  instead  of  two. 

Geometrical  necessity  has  long  been  the  great 
stumbling-block  of  both  the  rival  philosophies.  The 
sensationalists'  doctrine  that  necessary  truths  come 
from  "  irresistible  association  "  seems  almost  farcical. 


SCIENCE  01    I  HOUGH!  . 

The  idealists  having  generally  lost  faith  in  their 
"innate  ideas  "  and  "intuitions,"  have  taken  refuge  in 
Kant's  paradox  that  space  is  ideal.  Dispensing  with 
all  such  strange  devices,  we  have  found  geometrical 

isity  to  depend  solely  upon  the  nature  of  spa 
neither  changing  nor  causing  change. 

Corollary  /.  Dugald  Stewart  pointed  out  and  it  is 
about  the  only  real  gleam  of  light  heretofore  thrown 
upon  the  problem — that  we  more  readily  and  clearly 
perceive  the  truth  of  the-  particular  instances  embraced 
under  an  axiom,  than  the  truth  of  the  axiom  itself.  Now, 
if  axioms  were  intuitions  the  converse  of  this  would 
surely  happen.  Hut  our  doctrine  explains  the  fact 
just  as  it  stands.  We  clearly  and  instantaneously 
perceive  the  truth  of  the  particular  instance  because 
it  depends  upon  nothing  but  the  nature  of  thought 
dealing  with  the  idea  of  space-.  The  axiom,  which  is 
but  an  abstract  and  generalized  statement  of  the  par- 
ticular instances,  comes  later  and  is  less  clearly  recog- 
nized. 

Corollary  2.  Time  is  to  be  explained  precisely  as 
space  has  been.  By  following  the  explanation  of 
space  just  given,  the  reader  can  readily  work  out  the 
problem  of  time  for  himself. 


CHAPTER    IV. 
CONCEPTS. 

Every  concept  has  two  meanings.  The  one  is  its 
meaning  in  intension,  pointing  out  the  characteristics 
of  the  class;  the  other  its  meaning  in  extension  refer- 
ring to  the  different  individuals  or  objects  included 
within  the  class.  All  logicians  have  recognized  and 
used  this  familiar  distinction;  but  they  have  been 
strangely  blind  to  its  supreme  importance  as  disclos- 
ing the  inmost  nature  of  the  concept.  It  remains  for 
me  to  show  that  these  two  meanings — these  two  con- 
stituent elements  of  every  general  notion — are  related 
to  each  other  as  cause  and  effect. 

For,  firstly,  the  intension  of  a  concept  determines 
its  extension.  What  objects  may  be  included  within 
a  class,  depends  upon  the  attributes  of  that  class. 
The  extension  gives  us  objects  classified;  the  intension 
points  to  the  ground  or  cause  of  their  classification. 
This  by  itself  would  be  sufficient  to  prove  our  thesis; 
but  we  can  go  farther.  We  can  show  that  the  inten- 
sive meaning  points  to  a  dimly  disclosed  unity  and 
permanence,  the  properties  of  causality;  that  the  ex- 
tensive meaning  points  to  a  clearly  apparent  multi- 
plicity and  change,  the  properties  of  effects. 

For,  secondly,  the  intension  is  always  a  unit.  That 
is  so,  of  course,  when  the  concept  has  but  one  at- 
tribute. And  although  a  natural  kind  may  have  a 
countless  number  of   attributes,  they  are   always  con- 


2  |  S<  IENCE   I  »i     I  HOUGHT. 

ceived  as  one  set  as  a  co-ordinated  system  as  a 
unit}-  so  definitely  fixed   that   from  the  presence  oi  a 

few  of    the    attributes    we    can    always    infer    the    rest. 

The  extension,  on  tin-  contrary,  refers  to  a  mere  mul- 
tiplicity, a  multitude  which  never  has  hem  and  never 
can  hi'  brought  together  at  one  time  <>r  place. 

Thirdly,  the  intension  is  permanent*  The  set  of 
attributes  does  not  change  from  century  to  century; 
it  is  a  combination  of  qualities  fixed  and  uniform  for 
every  possible  member  of  the  class.  Hut  the  exten- 
sion of  a  concept  is  the  very  type  of  variablene 
includes  both  the  actual  and  the  possible,  things  past, 
present  and  to  come;  it  designates  a  multitude  in 
continual  flux. 

Fourthly,  the  intensive  meaning  is  less  apparent 
than  the  extensive.  Hast}-  and  superficial  thought 
always  conceives  of  a  class  merely  as  a  collection  of 
objects;  it  continually  loses  sight  of  that  deeper 
meaning  of  the  concept,  without  which  the  first  would 
be  but  mere  nonsense.  The  history,  of  logical  specu- 
lation for  centuries  has  proved  that. 

Every  concept,  therefore,  contains  two  meanings 
related  to  each  other  as  cause  and  effect. 

The  exposition  just  given  of  the  concept,  has  many 
uses.  But  above  all  else,  it  puts  an  end  to  that  most 
ancient  and  perplexing  of  all  logical  controversies — 
the  dispute  between  the  Realists  or  their  modern  suc- 
cessors and  the  Nominalists.  For  it  can  now  be  shown 
that  both  of  these  rival  systems  are  equally  at  fault, 
both  equally  one-sided  and  defective. 

Each  of  the  two  meanings  of  a  concept  must,  by  it- 


CONCEPTS.  25 

self,  be  vague,  elusive  and  incomplete.  Each  forms 
but  one-half  or  one  side  of  a  perfect  concept;  each  be- 
comes fully  intelligible  only  when  related  to  the  other. 
Now,  both  of  the  rival  logical  systems  ignore,  so  far 
as  possible,  this  double  import  of  the  concept.  Nom- 
inalism lays  an  exclusive  emphasis  upon  the  meaning 
in  extension.  Realism  orConceptualism — for  the  two 
differ  in  degree,  not  in  kind — lays  its  emphasis  upon 
the  meaning  in  intension.  Each,  therefore,  fails  to 
give  a  true  and  adequate  explanation  of  general  no- 
tions. 

Realism  and  Conceptualism,  revolving  around  the 
intensive  meaning  of  the  concept,  have  spun  an  amaz- 
ing web  of  subtilties.  But  the  incomparable  skill  of 
Berkeley  proved  long  ago  that  we  cannot  form  any 
clear  and  complete  idea  of  any  attribute  or  set  of  at- 
tributes, isolated  from  the  idea  of  some  concrete  ob- 
ject possessing  that  attribute  or  set  of  attributes.  By 
no  effort  of  thought  can  we  form  a  full  and  distinct 
idea  of  "man"  or  of  the  human  attributes  apart  from  the 
idea  of  some  individual  man;  or  of  "motions"  inde- 
pendently of  the  idea  of  some  moving  body.  All  that 
is  irrefragably  true;  and  thereby  the  whole  ground  of 
Realism  is  swept  away.  These  isolated  abstractions, 
— these  scholastic  universals  and  "quiddities"  and  the 
more  modern  "bundles  of  attributes"  —  are  but  half- 
ideas  which  can  exist  in  thought  only  in  conjunction 
with  their  complements.  Causes  in  themselves,  un- 
related to  their  effects,  are  unknowable  and  unthink- 
able. 


26  SCIENl  i    01     I  HOUGH!  . 

The  Nominalist  goes  to  the  other  extreme.  In  his 
zeal  for  the  meaning  in  extension  he  paradoxically 
affirms  that  there  are  no  general  notions  only  gen- 
eral terms  or  common  names  for  different  objects. 
He  forgets  that  a  name  could  not  be  common  to  differ- 
ent objects  unless  they  resembled  each  other  in  cer- 
tain respects.  Therefore,  even  the  common  name 
has  a  double  import  :  on  the  one  side  it  points  to  dif- 
ferent objects;  on  the  other  to  the  respects  in  which 
they  resemble  each  other.  All  this  the  Nominalist 
ignores;  and  so  offers  an  explanation  of  the  classify- 
ing process  as  utterly  inadequate  as  it  is  paradoxical. 

Both  the  rival  systems,  then,  are  equally  defective. 
Their  controversy  is  a  wrangle  over  opposite  sides  of 
the  same  truth.  We  shall  never  gain  a  true  theory 
of  classification  until  we  recognize  the  double  import 
of  the  concept,  and  remember  that  each  of  its  two 
meanings  is  fully  intelligible  only  when  related  to  the 
other. 

We  have  proved  our  law,  then,  so  far  as  concepts 
are  concerned,  and  this  would  be  sufficient,  by  itself, 
to  prove  it  in  regard  to  all  processes  of  thought. 
For  all  thinking  is  carried  on  by  means  of  concepts. 

Corollary  i.  This  law  of  the  complexity  of  con- 
cepts explains  why  language  is  indispensable  for  gen- 
uine thinking.  On  account  of  its  double  import,  a 
concept  cannot  be  clearly  held  before  the  mind,  ex- 
cept through  the  intervention  of  a  verbal  sign. 

Corollary  2.  Brutes  have  no  language  because 
they  have  need  of  none.  They  receive  impressions 
from  the  outer  world  and  doubtless  these  impressions 


CONCEPTS.  27 

are  combined  and  transformed  by  something  like  the 
laws  of  association.  In  fact,  I  am  inclined  to  believe 
that  what  "the  association-philosophy"  describes  and 
explains  as  thinking,  forms  a  pretty  faithful  picture  of 
what  takes  place  in  the  brain  of  the  animal.  .  But 
there  is  no  shadow  of  proof,  or  even  of  probability 
that  a  brute  can  form  an  idea — that  is,  a  general  no- 
tion with  its  synthesis  of  cause  and  effect.  Therefore 
animals  have  no  need  of  speech;  nor  could  use  it  if 
possessed. 


CHAPTER  V. 
SCIENCE. 

In  considering  the  theory  of  reasoning,  I  shall    pass 

by  many  minor  questions  to  come  to  the  most  difficult 
and  important  one.  What  is  the  inductive  or  scien- 
tific method?  That  question  has  been  often  asked 
and  never  answered.  Although  the  scientific  method 
has  been  used  so  long  and  with  such  magnificent  re- 
sults, there  is  something  about  it  that  has  heretofore 
eluded  description  and  defied  analysis.  And  it  may 
seem  mere  arrogance  to  attempt  in  four  or  five  pages, 
the  solution  of  a  problem  that  has  baffled  the  logical 
skill  of  centuries.  But  the  light  which  has  led  us  so 
far,  will  not  desert  us  here. 

There  are  but  two  kinds  of  reasoning,  deduction 
and  induction;  and  both  of  them  have  a  certain  ap- 
pearance of  imperfection  and  inadequateness.  Deduc- 
tion, as  every  logician  knows,  has  long  labored  under 
the  reproach  of  being  essentially  nothing  more  than  a 
begging  of  the  question.  The  inference,  it  is  said, 
really  infers  nothing;  all  that  is  affirmed  in  the  conclu- 
sion has  been  already  affirmed  in  the  premises.  The 
objection  is  difficult  to  answer;  and  even  if  we  set  it 
aside,  we  must  still  admit  that  deduction  is  an  incom- 
plete and  inadequate  process.  The  chief  value  of 
syllogistic  reasoning  depends  upon  the  accuracy  of  the 
premises,  and  with  that  the  deduction  has  nothing  to 
do.      The  deduction  by  itself  is  a  singularly  simple,  a 


SCIENCE.  29 

purely  formal  and  mechanical  act  which  could  proba- 
bly be  done  by  a  machine  as  well  as  by  a  human  being. 
In  mathematics,  indeed,  deductive  reasoning  has  done 
marvelous  things;  but  the*  marvel  is  due  to  the  human 
ingenuity  which  has  combined  a  great  number  of  sim- 
ple and  trivial  deductions  into  a  complicated  and 
splendid  chain  of  reasoning;  just  as  a  beautiful  build- 
ing may  be  constructed  out  of  rude  and  diminutive 
stones.  And  the  whole  history  of  thought  proves  that 
outside  the  mathematical  sciences,  pure  deduction 
tends  to  vain  disputations  and  idle  subtilities  rather 
than  to  the  discovery  of  truth.  Thus  logically  and 
historically  a  syllogism  is  shown  to  be  by  itself  a  most 
imperfect  and  futile  act  of  reasoning;  it  takes  its  prem- 
ises for  granted,  and  then  does  nothing  but  formally 
and  mechanically  assert  in  the  conclusion  what  it  had 
already  assumed  in  the  premises. 

Pure  induction  is  still  more  obviously  defective.  It 
carries  a  fallacy  upon  its  very  face;  to  conclude  from 
particulars  to  universals  is  a  plain  violation  of  all  logi- 
cal rules.  The  ingenuity  of  ages  has  failed  to  clear 
induction  from  this  appearance  of  utter  irrationality. 
No  one  has  yet  shown  how  in  the  actual,  physical 
world  purely  contingent  experience  can  be  logically 
transmuted  into  universal  and  necessary  law.  More- 
over, history  proves  that  pure  induction  is  fatally  mis- 
leading: the  greater  part  of  human  ignorance  and  sup- 
erstition has  sprung  from  this  tendency  of  the  mind 
to  conclude  from  particulars  to  universals. 

Both  deduction  and  induction,  then,  are  equally  de- 
fective  and    misleading.      Logicians   have   long  been 


30  SCIENCE  OF   THOUGHT. 

dimly  aware  of  this  fact,  although  for  the  credit  of 
their  science  they  have  been  inclined  to  ignore  it  or 
to  obscure  it  by  futile  explanations.  Hut  there  is  no 
need  of  being  alarmed  at  this,  as  if  the  very  founda- 
tions of  truth  were  about  to  be  undermined.  On  the 
contrary,  by  the  recognition  of  this  fact,  we  are  brought 
face  to  face  with  that  fundamental  law  which  governs 
the  whole  realm  of  thought  and  gives  it  perfection. 
Both  causes  by  themselves  and  effects  by  themselves 
are  unknowable;  the  effort  to  know  them  thus,  results 
only  in  vague,  inadequate  half  thoughts.  And  it  inev- 
itably follows  from  this,  that  both  pure  deduction,  or 
reasoning  from  causes  alone,  and  pure  induction,  or 
reasoning  from  effects  alone,  are  essentially  imperfect 
and  invalid  processes. 

And  thus  we  arrive  at  the  long-sought  definition  of 
the  scientific  method.  Exact  knowledge  or  science 
can  be  attained  only  by  a  synthesis  of  deduction  and 
induction  whereby  each  of  these  two  processes,  by  it- 
self defective,  is  strengthened  and  supported  by  the 
other.  The  scientific  method  consists  in  such  a  syn- 
thesis. 

The  first  process  is  one  of  pure  induction  from  par- 
ticulars to  universals.  We  observe  that  a  certain  co- 
existence or  sequence  of  phenomena  is  uniformly  re- 
peated; and  this  observed  uniformity  we  boldly  trans- 
form into  a  law.  Thus  empirical  rules  are  formed, 
often  crude  and  dubious,  but  sometimes  attaining  to  a 
high  degree  of  certainty.  Hut  still  something  is  lack- 
ing.     The  deep  chasm  between  an  empirical  rule  and 


SCIENCE.  31 

a  universal  law  can  be  closed  only  by  the   second  pro- 
cess of  the  scientific  method. 

The  second  process  is  deductive;  it  seeks  the  cause 
of  these  observed  uniformities;  in  otherwords  it  strives 
to  deduce  the  empirical  rule  from  some  more  univer- 
sal law.  Now,  if  this  wider  law  has  been  already  es- 
tablished, the  matter  is  simple  enough;  but  in  many 
cases  this  is  not  so.  Often  the  cause  is  but  hypothe- 
tical, merely  a  mathematical  formula  from  which  the 
empirical  rules  or  facts  may  be  deduced.  And  the 
question  arises,  how  scientific  certainty  is  gained 
through  this  subsumption  of  the  minor  laws  under  the 
more  universal  one?  I  answer,  firstly,  a  wider  interde- 
pendenceof  phenomena  is  thereby  established;  and  thus 
mere  co-incidence  is  less  apt  to  be  mistaken  for  invar- 
iable and  necessary  order.  Secondly,  exceptions  are 
gotten  rid  of;  what  is  inexplicable  by  the  minor  empir- 
ical rule,  often  admits  of  ready  explanation  under  the 
light  of  the  universal  law.  Thirdly  and  most  impor- 
tant of  all,  qualitative  laws  are  thus  converted  into 
quantitative  ones.  It  is  the  noblest  characteristic  of 
nature— one  to  which  we  owe  almost  all  our  real  knowl- 
edge of  her  secrets — that  her  deepest  and  widest  laws 
are  mathematical.  In  chemistry,  for  instance,  the 
most  intricate  and  obscure  qualitative  differences  have 
been  almost  magically  resolved  into  simple  equa-. 
tions  of  quantity.  Thus,  a  vast  increase  of  cer- 
tainty is  gained.  For  uniformities  of  quantity,  of 
weight  or  distance  can  be  measured  with  the  utmost 
minuteness;  so  that  a  single  observation  agreeing  with 


32  SCIENCE   « »i     I  M<  lUGHl  . 

a  mathematical  computation  becomes  of  far  more  value 
than  a  hundred  co-existences  oi  mere  quality. 

Such  then  is  the  scientific  method.  It  is  com- 
pounded of  two  elements  or  processes  induction  and 
deduction— each  by  itself  imperfect  and  invalid,  but 
together  forming  a  perfect  act  of  scientific  reasoning. ' 

In  a  word,  the  scientific  method  is  like  an  arch,  nei- 
ther side  of  which  could  stand  if  it  were  not  supported 
by  the  other. 

To  follow  out  all  the  applications  of  this  theory 
of  science  would  demand  a  volume  instead  of  these 
few  pages.  I  can  pause  only  to  note  that  our  doctrine 
will  be  signally  verified  in  the  chapters  upon  civiliza- 
tion. It  will  then  be  found  to  solve  that  chief  prob- 
lem in  the  history  of  science — the  utter  failure  of  ar- 
tiquity  except  at  Alexandria,  in  the  study  of  Nature; 
and  the  swift,  wondrous  triumph  of  modern  scientific 
research.  But  our  present  object  has  been  fully  ac- 
complished. The  principle  that  thinking  is  com- 
pounded of  two  elements,   each  inadequate  without  the 

lIt  may  be  objected  to  our  doctrine  of  the  inadequacy  of  deduction; 
that  mathematical  science  is  entirely  deductive.  But,  that  is,  although 
a  very  common,  an  erroneous  view.  The  chief  toil  of  the  mathe- 
matician is  inductive  or  inventive,  the  finding  of  his  premises. 
In  algebra,  for  instance,  and  generally  in  the  higher  and  applied  math- 
ematics— the  work  is  nearly  done  when  the  proper  equation  is  formed; 
that  is,  when  the  particular  instance  or  problem  has  been  put  under 
some  universal  formula  or  equation.  And  the  resolution  of  a  com- 
mon equation — that  is,  the  deductive  part — is  an  almost  mechanical 
process.  In  geometry  all  this  is  greatly  obscured,  because  its  ordinary 
study  is  confined  chiefly  to  following  and  memorizing  what  has  been 
already  done.  But  in  the  formation  of  geometry — and  in  its  proper 
study  too — the  chief  matter  was  the  statement  of  its  problems,  the 
finding  out  by  experiment  of  the  premises  from  which  to  deduce. 


SCIENCE.  33 

other,  has  been  vindicated  so  far  as  scientific  reason- 
ing is  concerned.  All  perfect  thought  from  the  sim- 
plest act  of  perception  up  to  the  most  elaborate  pro- 
cesses of  scientific  research,  has  been  found  to  have  a 
common  nature  and  to  be  governed  by  one  fundamen- 
tal law. 
3 


CIIAI'TKK    VI. 

MORALITY. 

Morality  is  compounded  of  two  elements — the  con- 
sciousness of  causality  and  the  foresight  of  conse- 
quences. A  true  ethical  system  would  hold  both  of 
these  elements  in  that  perfect  synthesis  which  the 
nature  of  thought  demands.  But  instead  of  that  we 
find  moralists  divided  into  two  rival  schools,  each  of 
which  emphasizes  what  the  other  ignores.  On  the 
one  side  are  the  realists  ignoring  and  even  denying  the 
consciousness  of  causality  ;  on  the  other  are  the  ideal- 
ists eager  to  construct  an  ethical  theory  that  shall 
ignore,  so  far  as  possible,  the  consequences  of  conduct. 
Thus  both  systems  become  equally  one-sided  and  de- 
fective ;  controversy  and  confusion  reign  everywhere 
in  ethical  philosophy. 

Seeking  now  a  way  out  of  this  confusion,  let  us  be- 
gin with  the  doctrine  of  the  realists.  These  deny  the 
human  consciousness  of  self-causality,  upon  two  gen- 
eral grounds  which  we  will  consider  in  turn. 

(i)  The  realists  assert  that  self-causality  is  incon- 
ceivable. The  self,  according  to  Jonathan  Edwards 
and  others  of  his  school,  cannot  be  the  determining 
cause  of  its  own  volitions,  because  "it  is  inconceivable 
that  the  same  cause  in  the  same  circumstances  should 
produce  different  effects  at  different  times. "  The  mind 
can  act  only  in  that  way  in  which  it  has  been  deter- 
mined to  act  by  antecedent  circumstances. 


MORALITY.  35 

But  this  alleged  inconceivability  is  a  mere  prejudice 
and  an  utter  delusion.  It  is  true  enough  that  no 
material  thing  can  act  in  different  ways  under  the 
same  conditions  ;  for,  being  unconscious,  it  cannot 
present  before  itself  the  two  courses  of  action  between 
which  it  would  have  to  decide.  Its  act  must  be  de- 
termined for  it  by  something  beyond  itself.  But  it  is 
simply  absurd  to  assume  that  because  this  is  true  in 
regard  to  unconscious  being,  it  must  also  be  true  in 
regard  to  conscious  being.  Does  the  fact  that  beings 
without  eyes  are  unable  to  see,  prove  that  beings  with 
eyes  are  also  unable  to  see?  No  more  does  the  fact 
that  the  unconscious  cannot  determine  itself,  prove  that 
the  conscious  cannot  determine  itself. 

The  assertion  that  self-causality  is  inconceivable, 
has  its  origin  in  a  double  error.  In  the  first  place, 
the  realist  mistakes  the  incomprehensibility  of  a 
method  for  the  inconceivableness  of  a  fact.  It  is,  in- 
deed, incomprehensible  how  a  conscious  being  deter- 
mines itself  to  either  one  of  two  possible  courses  of 
action.  But  it  is  equally  incomprehensible  how  the 
unconscious  is  determined  to  act  by  something  without 
itself.  In  the  last  resort  it  is  always  inscrutable  how 
things  happen  ;  we  only  know  that  they  do  happen. 

The  realist,  in  the  second  place,  is  infatuated  with 
a  passion  for  annulling  all  distinctions  between  mental 
and  physical  phenomena.  It  is  unendurable,  he  thinks, 
that  there  should  be  such  a  contrast  between  physical 
and  moral  causation.  But  he  forgets  that  this  differ- 
ence is  necessarily  involved  in  the  difference  between 
the  unconscious  and  the*  conscious.      The  first,  as  we 


36  SCIENCE    OF  THOUGHT. 

have  seen,  cannot  determine  itself,  because  it  is  uncon- 
scious ;  the  second  can  determine   itself,  because  it  is 

conscious.       Surely   then,    there    is  nothing  anomalous 
and  much  less  anything  inconceivable — in  tin's  differ- 
ence between  physical  and  moral  causation. 

There  does  not  appear   to  be  the  slightest  ground, 

then,  for  the  assertion  that  free  causation  is  inconceiv- 
able. And  yet  this  assertion  is  continually  being 
made  as  if  it  were  a  self-evident  truth. 

(2)  A  second  argument  exultantly  used  by  those 
who  deny  self-causality  is  the  argument  from  motives. 
They  affirm  that  every  moral  act  must  be  preceded  by 
a  motive  ;  as  Sir  William  Hamilton  has  tersely  said  : 
"A  motiveless  act  is  rationally  and  morally  worthless." 
All  that  may  gladly  be  conceded.  But  because  every 
moral  act  must  have  a  motive,  it  by  no  means  follows 
that  the  act  must  be  determined  or  necessitated  by 
the  motive.  And  secondly,  if  it  were  thus  determined, 
it  would  have  no  moral  worth.  If  an  act  without  a 
motive  is  morally  worthless,  so  also  is  an  act  mechani- 
cally determined  by  a  motive. 

This  refutation  is  summary,  but  it  is  unanswerable. 
The  object  of  this  volume,  however,  is  not  to  merely 
refute  fallacies,  but  to  explain  them  ;  and  so  something 
must  here  be  added.  Every  volition  contains,  in  fact, 
is  developed  from,  a  motive1 ;   but  the  mind   itself  de- 

1  This  explains  that  favorite  catch  used  by  the  determinists  as  a 
last  resort  :  I  cannot  act  so  and  so  unless  I  wish  to  ;  the  wish  or  desire 
therefore  is  the  antecedent  (See  Mills  Examination  of  Hamilton's 
Philosophy  II.  285  and  Logic  524,  for  examples).  Of  course  I  cannot 
will  unless  I  wish  to  ;  since  the  volition  is  but  the  developed  wish. 
But  it  by  no  means  follows  that  I  cannot  will  unless  I  am  compelled  to. 


MORALITY.  37 

termines  whether  that  development  shall  take  place  or 
not.  This  the  necessitarian  denies  ;  he  considers  the 
development  of  a  motive  into  a  volition  to  be  a  problem 
in  mechanics.  The  motive,  he  thinks,  passes  into  the 
volition  mechanically,  because  it  is  "stronger"  or 
"weightier"  than  any  other  desire  present  in  the  mind. 
But  why  does  he  make  this  strange  assumption?  Con- 
scious experience  certainly  tells  him  nothing  about  the 
mechanical  strength  or  weight  of  motives,  or  that  they 
are  thus  mechanically  developed  into  volition.  It 
teaches  the  exact  contrary. 

Why  then,  I  repeat,  does  the  necessitarian  make 
this  assumption?  Simply  because  he  is  still  entangled 
in  the  meshes  of  the  first  fallacy  treated  in  this  chap- 
ter. It  is  inconceivable  to  him  how  the  conscious  can 
act  differently  from  the  unconscious — how  the  conscious 
self  can  act  at  all  unless  it  is  mechanically  determined 
to  act  by  something  not  itself.  And  therefore  he  goes 
on  repeating  that  it  must  be  the  superior  "weight"  or 
"strength"  of  the  desire  which  compels  the  mind  to 
develop  it  into  a  volition. 

The  whole  necessitarian  argument  thus  resolves  it- 
self into  a  single  fallacy.  All  its  elusive  proofs  and 
winding  subtilities  revolve  around  the  assumption  that 
conscious  or  free  causality  is  inconceivable.  In  a 
word,  necessitarian  morality  is  but  a  phase  of  that 
one-sided  realistic  tendency  which  ignores  the  cause 
and  dwells  only  upon  the  effect.1 

1  I  have  not  noticed  a  third  necessitarian  argument  —  that  from 
the  predictibility  of  conduct — on  account  of  its  excessive  vagueness. 
It  is  true  that  when  a  person's  character  is  known  his  future  conduct 


38  S<  IEN<  l.  OF    THOUGHT. 

The  idealists,  then,  arc  right  in  affirming  that  the 

mind  is  conscious  of  its  own  causality.  And  in  affirm- 
ing this  they  furnish  the  basis,  at  least,  oi  a  true  moral 
system. 

For,  the  idea  of  right  and  wrong,  as  distinguished 
from  the  idea  of  the  expedientand  the  inexpedient,  is 
necessarily  involved  in  this  consciousness  of  self-caus- 
ality. Because  we  arc  the  free  causes  of  our  actions, 
we  know  that  we  arc  responsible  for  them  ;  and  that 
not  in  the  merely  legal  sense  that  we  are  liable  to 
punishment,  but  in  the  moral  sense  that  we  deserve 
punishment.  We  not  only  fear  that  we  shall  be  pun- 
ished, but  we  recognize  that  we  ought  to  be.  To  the 
mere  fear  of  consequences  is  added  the  bitterness 
remorse  or  self-reproach.  We  say  to  ourselves  :  It  is 
just  ;  I  deserve  this  suffering  ;  I  have  brought  it  upon 
myself.  In  this  feeling  of  moral  responsibility  or 
desert,  the  idea  of  right  and  wrong  is  rooted. 

No  system,  whi'ch  denies  our  consciousness  of  self- 
causality,  can  ever  logically  pass  from  the  idea  of  the 
expedient  to  the  idea  of  the  right.  It  can  give  to  us 
the  foresight  and  fear  of  consequences,  but  never  the 
sense  of  desert  and  true  moral  responsibility.  All  its 
ingenious  sophistries  can  never  bridge  the  impassable 
chasm  between  the  mere  fear  that  we  shall  be  punished 
and  the  conviction  that  we  ought  to  be  punished.  If 
we  are    driven    into   suffering,    as  the  winds  and  stars 

may  be  guessed — not  by  any  means  predicted  in  the  scientific  sense  of 
the  word.  But  this  proves  only  what  no  one  denies.  The  mind  is 
continually  yielding  to  these  influences,  habit,  heredity,  or  environ- 
ment.    But  the  sane  mind  is  never  compelled  thus  to  yield. 


MORALITY.  39 

are  driven  in  their  courses  by  causes  beyond  their 
control,  we  may  shrink  from  the  pain,  but  we  shall 
have  no  more  sense  of  guilt  than  the  winds  and  stars 
have.      Recoil  from  pain  is  not  the  sense  of  desert. 

Up  to  this  point  then,  idealism  is  abundantly  justi- 
fied. But  it  is  fatally  defective  and  one-sided  in  that 
it  ignores,  so  far  as  possible,  the  other  element  of  mor- 
ality, the  foresight  of  consequences.  For  moral  laws, 
just  as  much  as  physical  ones,  can  be  established  only 
by  experience,  by"  the  study  of  effects  or  consequences. 
One  cannot  but  smile  at  the  futile  endeavors  of  the 
idealists  to  evolve  ethical  precepts  from  their  inner 
consciousness,  from  "intuitions;"  or  some  other  mys- 
tical a  priori  process  of  thought.  All  history  demon- 
strates the  vanity  of  such  endeavors.  Everywhere, 
among  different  races  and  in  different  ages  we  behold 
a  vast  diversity  and  variation  of  moral  judgments. 
And  such  uniformity  as  we  do  find,  is  manifestly  the 
result,  not  of  "intuition,"  but  of  that  moral  training  to 
which  society  subjects  its  members  from  childhood  to 
old  age. 

The  utilitarians  or  realists,  then,  are  right  when 
they  insist  that  the  only  test  or  criterion  of  conduct  is 
its  consequences.  The  consciousness  of  causality  gives 
us  the  universal  idea  of  right  or  wrong  ;  but  it  does 
not  tell  us  how  that  universal  idea  is  to  be  applied  to 
particular  actions.  In  regard  to  that,  experience  is 
our  only  teacher.  True  moral  laws  can  be  established 
only  by  closely  observing  the  effects  of  conduct  upon 
human  happiness.  A  morality  that  attempts  to  estab- 
lish its  precepts  in  any  other   way,  will  necessarily  be 


40  SCIENCE    OF  THOUGHT. 

wreak,  vague,  confused  and  fantastic.  It  will  lack  a 
correct  appreciation  of  the  different  virtues.  It  will 
not  have  that  moral  vigor  which  comes  only  from  clear 
and  exact  perceptions  of  moral  truth.  It  may  be  per- 
vaded by  a  deep  sense  of  sin  and  of  responsibility  to 
the  higher  powers,  but  it  will  be  very  poorly  fitted  to 
meet  the  actual  needs  of  human  life.  All  that  is  clearly 
evident  from  the  very  nature  of  the  case  ;  and  it  will 
be  remarkably  verified  in  the  chapters  upon  the  history 
of  civilization. 

Our  fundamental  law,  then,  is  again  vindicated. 
Both  the  old  ethical  theories  are  mutilated,  one-sided 
systems,  because  each  ignores  one  or  the  other  of  the 
two  indispensable  elements  of  thought.  The  true 
theory  will  combine  both  elements,  cause  and  effect. 
It  will  recognize  the  consciousness  of  causality  as  fur- 
nishing the  only  basis  of  morality  ;  and  the  foresight 
of  consequences  as  establishing  moral  rules  and  thus 
providing  the  ethical  superstructure.  The  result  will 
not  be  a  barren  eclecticism  selecting  its  doctrines  at 
random,  but  a  true  ethical  system  governed  by  that 
law  which  rules  the  whole  world  of  thought. 


CHAPTER    VII. 
ART. 

Hardly  any  one  will  deny  that  there  is  as  yet  no 
science  of  the  beautiful.  Many  aesthetic  theories  have 
been  advanced,  received  with  favor  by  some,  rejected 
by  others,  and  then  have  passed  into  oblivion.  But 
despite  all  these  failures,  an  aesthetic  science  is  still 
possible.  The  principle  which  has  been  found  to  rule 
in  every  other  realm  of  thought,  rules  here  also.  And 
it  will  enable  us  to  define  the  nature  of  beauty,  to 
discover  that  common  characteristic  in  all  beautiful 
things  which  imparts  to  them  their  charm.  Thus  we 
shall  have,  at  last,  the  basis  of  a  true  aesthetic  science. 

We  have  seen  that  there  are  two  intellectual  tenden- 
cies, each  representative  of  one  side  or  element  of 
perfected  thought.  The  one  tendency  is  absorbed  in 
the  contemplation  of  effects,  is  intent  upon  that  ap- 
pearance of  multiplicity  and  change  so  visible  upon 
the  very  surface  of  things  ;  the  other  tendency  seeks 
rather  for  causes — for  that  manifestation  of  power, 
unity  and  permanence  which  is  not  so  apparent  indeed, 
but  still  is  exhibited  in  every  part  of  the  universe. 
Both  of  these  forms  of  mental  activity  are  to  a  certain 
extent  pleasurable  ;  and  the  pleasures  attendant  upon 
them,  we  may  call  for  lack  of  better  terms,  the  one, 
realistic,  the  other,  idealistic  emotion. 

Let  it  now  be  noted  that  each  of  these  pleasures  is, 
by  itself,    transient,    and  so  essentially  imperfect  that 


42  SCIENCE   OB    THOUGH  I ". 

it  is  ever  liable  to  pass  into  a  pain.  We  arc  pie; 
for  a  while,  by  variety  and  novelty  ;  but  the  mind 
grows  bewildered,  distracted  and  irritated  by  the  con- 
fusion and  din  of  mere  change.  There  is  a  certain 
charm  also  in  the  recognition  of  causal  power  with  its 
unity  and  invariableness  ;  but  very  soon  this  uniform 
order  becomes  for  us  a  tedious,  Oppressive  and  insuf- 
ferable monotony.  Each  feeling,  then,  by  itself,  is 
defective,  spasmodic,  powerless  to  impart  full  and 
abiding  enjoyment.  Hut  when  the  two  feelings  are 
combined,  so  as  to  relieve  and  support  each  other,  we 
have  that  most  exalted  of  all  emotions— tranquil  and 
sustained  delight  in  the  beautiful. 

These  two  balanced  feelings,  it  will  be  remembered, 
differ  ;  firstly,  in  their  objects,  power,  unity  and  per- 
manence upon  the  one  side,  multiplicity  and  change 
upon  the  other;  secondly,  in  the  fact  that  the  percep- 
tion is  more  obscure  in  the  one  case  than  the  other. 
This  understood,  we  have  the  definition  so  long  sought 
but  never  found.  The  beautiful  is  that  which  harmon- 
izes realistic  and  idealistic  emotion. 

It  remains  now  to  verify  this  aesthetic  theory  by 
showing,  first,  that  it  will  explain  the  chief  aesthetic 
rules  and  convictions  which  have  long  been  empirically 
recognized  in  the  world  of  art  ;  and  secondly,  that  it 
will  also  satisfactorily  account  for  the  emotions  of  the 
ludicrous  and  the  sublime — those  half-sisters,  as  it 
were,  of  the  beautiful. 


(i)   The  curve   has  always  been   recognized  as  the 
line  of   beauty.      This    first  and    most  comprehensive 


ART.  43 

rule  of  aesthetic  form  has  heretofore  been  empirically 
accepted  as  an  ultimate,  inexplicable  fact  ;  but  from 
our  present  point  of  view  it  readily  submits  to  analy- 
sis and  explanation.  For,  the  curve  has  two  essential 
characteristics;  first,  it  is  a  line  continually  changing 
its  direction;  second,  these  incessant  changes  are  gov- 
erned by  a  simple  and  invariable  law.  It  is  thus  the 
perfect  type  of  that  balance  between  the  two  elements 
of  thought  which  our  law  demands.  It  is  neither 
straight  nor  crooked,  nor  partially  the  one  and  par- 
tially the  other,  nor  any  other  absurd  equation  of  con- 
tradictories. It  is  perfect  order  and  perfect  change 
related  to  each  other  as  cause  and  effect.  The  curved 
line,  in  a  word,  is  the  visible  embodiment  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  all  beauty  and  of  all  perfected  thought. 

We  may  go  farther  in  our  analysis  and  thereby  ex- 
plain the  different  aesthetic  values  of  different  kinds  of 
curvation.  Thus,  according  to  Hogarth,  "the  serpen- 
tine line"  is  pre-eminently  beautiful;  while  straight 
lines  are  too  lean  and  poor  and  circles  or  lines  nearly 
circular  are  too  gross.  The  rules  thus  laid  down  by 
the  great  artist  are  manifestly  true;  but  the  explan- 
ation of  them  is  rather  that  of  a  portrait-painter  than 
of  a  philosopher.  Circles  displease  not  on  account  of 
their  grossness  or  fatness,  but  because  they  violate, 
in  one  chief  respect,  the  principle  of  beauty.  For,  in 
them  the  element  of  uniformity  is  so  obtrusively  mani- 
fest as  to  completely  obscure  the  element  of  variety 
and  change;  it  requires  no  little  thought  to  perceive 
the  continuous  change  of  direction  involved  in  a  circle. 
Thus  the   law  of  beauty   is  exactly   reversed.      That 


44  SCIENCE   OF   THOUGHT. 

law  demands,  as  we  have  seen,  that  the  element  of 
variety  and  change  should  be  clearly  and  superficially 
apparent,  while  the  element  of  unity  and  invariableness 
must  be  more  obscurely  presented.  This  relation  be- 
tween clear  and  dim  perception  is  of  the  very  essence 
of  the  beautiful. 

(2)  What  constitutes  that  charm  of  color  felt  at 
once  by  the  savage  and  the  civilized,  but  which  has 
never  been  explained  except  as  inexplicably  "organic'' 
or  "primitive"?  But  the  scientific  explanation  is  now 
not  far  to  seek.  For,  firstly,  color  is  the  most  vivid 
manifestation  possible  of  change  or  contrast;  in  fact, 
all  visible  differences  are  exhibited  to  us,  only  through 
the  medium  of  differently  colored  lines  or  surfaces. 
And,  secondly,  all  these  variations  are  governed  by  a 
simple  law  of  unity  or  gradation  whereby  one  shifting- 
hue  passes  into  another  with  infinite  grace  and  deli- 
cacy. The  rainbow  revealed  that  to  the  commonest 
mind,  long  before  there  was  any  science  of  optics. 
And  color  is  beautiful  because  it  is  thus  capable  of 
fully  satisfying  the  realistic  delight  in  change  or  con- 
trast and  the  idealistic  passion  for  unity  and  order. 

We  can  also  easily  explain  why  savages,  children 
and  the  uncultivated  take  such  delight  in  gaudy, 
glaring  colors.  Fdr  such  minds  are  captivated  by  the 
realistic  element  in  beauty  ;  they  love  the  contrast  and 
novelty  so  vividly  displayed  by  bright  colors.  But 
the  idealistic  element,  that  obscure  revelation  of  unity, 
gradation  and  repose  can  be  fully  appreciated  only  by 
the  thoughtful  and  the  artistic.  Compare,  for  in- 
stance, the  gradated  tints  of  the  rainbow  or  of  a  blush 


ART.  45 

mantling  a  fair  cheek  with  the  paint  on  the  face  of  a 
savage. 

(3)  The  beauty  of  sounds  manifestly  depends  upon 
the  same  law  of  synthesis.  Music  gives  us,  on  the 
one  hand,  an  ever  changing  succession  of  fleeting 
sounds  ;  on  the  other,  a  sense  of  regularity  pervading, 
more  or  less  obscurely,  this  mass  of  vocal  changes. 
The  first  element,  by  itself,  would  be  but  mere  noise, 
irregular  and  flitting,  which  would  soon  become  in- 
tensely irritating;  the  second,  by  itself,  would  soon 
pass  into  a  dull  and  oppressive  monotony.  But  the 
two  are  combined  even  in  the  crudest  forms  of  savage 
music,  and  far  more  perfectly  in  the  triumphs  of  mod- 
ern musical  art.  And  the  eternal  charm  of  music 
consists  in  its  wonderful  capacity  for  thus  combining 
those  realistic  emotions  which  stir  and  excite  the  soul, 
with  those  idealistic  ones  that  soothe  and  tranquilize 
it  by  their  suggestions  of  power,  unity  and  repose. 

(4)  Our  law  is  then  fully  verified  in  regard  to  those 
three  grand  divisions  of  aesthetic  theory,  the  beauty 
of  figure,  color  and  sound.  We  come  now  to  the  the- 
ory of  the  Fine  Arts.  And  here  we  need  only  to 
complete  Schiller's  celebrated  definition  of  Art  as  play. 
That  definition  precisely  expresses  one  side  or  element 
of  all  artistic  production. 

For,  play  has  three  essential  characteristics,  first,  it 
is  unconstrained;  if  it  was  carried  on  not  for  its  own 
sake,  but  under  the  constraint  of  some  useful  end,  it 
would  be  work.  Secondly,  play  is  imitative,  it  cares 
only  for  appearance,  lives  in  a  feigned  world  copied 
from    the   real    one.      Thirdly,  its  pleasure  is  that  af- 


46  SCIENCE   OF  THOUGHT. 

forded  by  change,  novelty,  release  from  the  dull  toil 
and  monotony  of  common  life.  Now,  we  have  already 
seen  that  these  three  characteristics  -delight  in  free- 
dom or  in  the  absence  of  constraining  and  regulative 
power,  delight  in  appearance  or  show  and  delight  in 
novelty — are  precisely  the  characteristics  of  realistic 
emotion.  This  is  the  philosophic  truth  involved  in 
Schiller's  definition. 

But  the  Fine  Arts  are  something  more  than  play. 
They  contain  also  an  element  of  seriousness,  of  pro- 
found thought,  of  strenuous  although  exalted  toil. 
True  art  must  give  at  least  some  suggestion  of  that 
regulative  power,  unity  and  repose  which  obscurely 
pervades  the  apparent  world  of  hap-hazard,  show  and 
change.  It  was  the  recognition  of  this  deeper  element 
in  art  which  made  Aristotle  say  so  grandly  that  poetry 
was  a  more  serious  and  philosophic  matter  than  phil- 
osophy itself.  In  a  word,  Art  must  combine  the  spirit 
of  play  and  of  seriousness  ;  it  must  gratify  both  realis- 
tic and  idealistic  emotion. 

I  can  here  note,  very  briefly,  a  few  of  the  many 
applications  of  this  doctrine.  First,  it  avoids  the  fatal 
defect  of  Schiller's  theory,  in  that  he  was  never  able 
to  precisely  define  the  difference  between  the  Fine 
Arts  and  other  kinds  of  play  that  are  anything  but 
artistic.  Whatever  gratifies  merely  the  delight  in  free- 
dom, mimicry  and  change,  is  play  and  nothing  more. 
Beautiful  play  or  art  begins  when  the  deeper  and  more 
serious  element  is  added. 

Secondly,  it  shows  that  art  is  something  more  than 
imitation.      There    may   be    the   utmost    realism,    the 


ART.  47 

most  vivid  and  photographic  copying  of  nature  and 
still  no  genuine  art.  Beyond  the  mere  play  or  imita- 
tive fancy,  there  must  be  that  creative  work  of  the 
imagination  which  idealizes  common  things,  imparts 
the  charm  of  unity  and  order  to  apparent  chaos, 
breathes,  as  it  were,  upon  the  dead,  incoherent  mass 
of  details  and  transforms  it  into  living  and  immortal 
beauty.  As  a  corollary  to  this,  comes  also  Lessing's 
famous  law  that  the  more  perfect  the  imitation  effected 
by  any  art,  the  narrower  is  its  range.  Sculpture,  for 
instance,  is  thus  confined  to  a  very  narrow  class  of 
objects.  And  the  explanation  is  now  easy  :  the  more 
perfect  the  realistic  imitation,  the  less  chance  for  ideal- 
istic suggestion. 

Thirdly,  another  essential  characteristic  of  art  is 
that  its  noblest  efforts  transcend  all  rules  and  technical 
processes.  This  too,  can  now  be  readily  explained. 
The  realistic  imitation  of  the  apparent  is  largely  me- 
chanical. But  the  other,  or  idealistic  element,  is  more 
dimly  perceived,  and  therefore  in  the  treatment  of  it 
rules  and  mechanical  processes  are  of  little  avail  ;  it 
can  be  known  and  expressed  only  by  the  subtle  power 
of  artistic  genius. 

(5)  That  distinction  between  fancy  and  imagination 
so  much  discussed  by  modern  criticism,  can  be  fully 
explained  only  by  our  theory.  The  difference  between 
them  I  find  to  be  that  the  one  clings  to  the  realistic 
element,  the  other  to  the  idealistic  element  in  beauty. 
For,  firstly,  fancy  is  pure  play;  she  has  no  depth  of 
feeling  or  earnestness  ;  but  imagination  is  ever  serious, 
intense,  speaks  from  the  heart  to  the  heart.     Secondly, 


48  SCIENCE   OF   THOUGHT. 

the  fancy  is  imitative  ;  she  delights  in  appearance, 
.md  pictures  the  exterior.  The  imagination  is 
creative,  reveals  the  inmost  nature  of  things.  Third]}', 
the  fancy  is  clear,  brilliant  ;  her  metaphors  play  like 
Lambent  flames  over  the  mere  surface  ol  things.  Hut 
the  imagination  is  prone  to  obscurity  ;  with  a  word 
sin-  dimly  suggests  things  unutterable  ;  with  a  few 
grand  strokes,  she  opens  up  exhaustless  thoughts  that 
flow  on  forever.  Fourthly,  the  fancy  works  by  rule, 
is  accurate,  elegant.  But  the  imagination  cares  little 
for  laws  or  conventional  forms  ;  she  breaks  the  casket 
in  order  to  get  the  jewels.  Fifthly,  the  fancy  delights 
in  multiplicity  and  details;  the  imagination  has  the 
secret  of  unity  and  comprehends  the  whole  with  a 
glance.  Sixthly,  the  fancy  is  fond  of  change  ;  is 
less,  feverish,  thirsts  for  startling  effects.  But  the 
very  essence  of  the  imagination  is  a  sublime  repose, 
quivering  with  the  pulses  of  a  hidden  power. 

Xo  one,  conversant  with  the  great,  incoherent  mass 
of  criticism  about  fancy  and  imagination,  will  deny 
that  the  essential  differences  between  the  two  are  cor- 
rectly portrayed  above.  And  they  obviously  corres- 
pond to  what  we  have  before  seen  to  be  the  differences 
between  the  realistic  and  the  idealistic  element  in 
beauty. 

(6)  The  ludicrous  has  been  generally  defined  as  the 
incongruous.  But  there  is  evidently  something  lack- 
ing in  this  definition,  for  the  incongruous  is  by  no 
means  always  laughable.  Many  unavailing  efforts 
have  been  made  to  supply  what  is  so  plainly  missing 
here.       Bain,    for    instance,    following    in    this    other 


ART.  49 

eminent  thinkers,  has  described  the  essence  of  the 
ludicrous  as  consisting  in  the  degradation  of  some- 
thing worthy.  But  that  plainly  is  to  confound  pure 
and  sweet  laughter  with  hateful  derision  and  ghoulish 
glee.  Evidently  the  true  definition  remains  still  to 
be  sought,  and  T  now  define  the  ludicrous  as  that 
which  produces  an  excess  of  realistic  emotion. 

Realistic  emotion,  as  we  have  seen,  depends  upon 
the  perception  of  variety  and  change.  When  both 
of  these  are  in  a  certain  excess,  when  variety  has  be- 
come incongruity  and  change  has  become  sudden, 
even  abrupt,  we  have  the  ludicrous.  A  tumble  into 
the  mud  is  made  ludicrous  by  the  incongruity  of  the 
position  and,  above  all,  by  its  abruptness  and  unex- 
pectedness. A  skilled  jester  wears  a  grave  face,  in 
order  to  make  the  perception  of  incongruity  as  ab- 
rupt as  possible.  We  smile  at  a  momentary  discord, 
but  when  long  continued  it  becomes  a  torture.  A 
drenching  is  ludicrous,  if  sudden  and  unexpected 
enough.  We  laugh  at  an  unexpected  act  of  folly, 
but  not  at  persistent  foolishness.  Wit  must  come  in 
flashes.  Repetition  wears  away  the  point  of  every 
joke,  and  converts  the  ludicrous  into  the  painful. 

Laughter,  then,  is  intense  realistic  emotion — de- 
light in  variety  and  change,  carried  to  the  extreme  of 
abrupt,  unexpected  incongruity.  The  full  force  of 
this  definition  appears  in  its  explanation  of  humor  or 
laughter  made  beautiful.  Humor  is  intense  realistic 
emotion  tempered  by  idealistic  seriousness.  The 
true  humorist  is  quick  to  perceive  the  incongruous 
and  unexpected,  but  he  is  equally  quick  to  perceive 
4 


50  SCI]  \<  E   OF   THOUGHT. 

that     latent     power     and     ideal     unity     of     human 

nature    hidden    beneath    these    superficial    and    fleeting 

aspects  of  weakness  and  folly.     And  among  all  the 

fine  arts  there  is  none  finer  than  that  which  thus 
harmonizes  the  spirit  of  laughter  and  play  with  a 
genial,  loving  sympathy  for  mankind. 

(7)  What,  now,  is  the  sublime  ?  The  definitions 
heretofore  given  seem  almost  ludicrously  inadequate. 
Many,  including  even  so  great  an  artistic  genius  as 
Hogarth,  have  described  the  essence  of  sublimity  as 
consisting  in  magnitude.  But  a  whale  is  not  sub- 
lime. Others  assert  that  the  essence  of  sublimity  is 
heighth.  But  the  sublimity  which  we  find  in  the 
Pyramids  we  should  not  find  in  a  pole  twice  as  high. 
Passing  by  other  equally  unsatisfactory  answers,  we 
present  the  solution  given  by  our  fundamental  law. 

Idealistic  emotion  we  have  found  to  be  delight  in 
the  dim  perception  of  power,  unity  and  permanence. 
Sublimity  is  this  feeling  carried  to  the  highest  in- 
tensity, but  still  relieved  by  the  counter-feeling.  The 
delight  in  power,  unity  and  permanence — the  ideal 
of  action,  space  and  time — must  be  relieved  by  de- 
light in  change  and  contrast  ;  otherwise  we  should 
have  only  the  dull,  depressing  sense  of  laborious 
effort,  sameness  and  monotony.  Instead  of  a  sense 
of  sublimity  we  should  have  only  an  unbalanced  and 
painful  feeling.  The  sublime,  then,  is  that  which 
produces  the  utmost  intensity  of  idealistic  emotion 
compatible  with  realistic  emotion. 

Countless  examples  might  be  given  to  show  that 
both   emotions   must   be   present.      The    ocean,    per- 


ART.  51 

fectly  and  perpetually  calm,  would  be  but  a  "big 
pond";  but  with  its  ever  changing  waves  and  storms, 
it  becomes  ineffably  sublime.  The  immeasurable 
vault  of  heaven  would  be  dull  enough,  if  its  sameness 
were  not  relieved  by  the  glitter  and  seeming  disorder 
of  the  stars.  The  mountains  are  made  sublime'  by 
their  eternal  repose  amidst  scenes  of  incessant  change. 
Acts  of  heroism  and  self-sacrifice  gain  their  grandeur 
from  their  contrast  with  the  common  level  of  human 
action.  The  thunder-storm,  above  all  else,  with  its 
awful  display  of  illimitable  power,  producing  the 
most  vivid  changes  and  contrasts — its  sudden  out- 
burst of  tremendous  energy  throughout  the  whole 
vast  and  stable  vault  of  heaven,  its  thick  darkness 
relieved  by  swift  flashes  of  lightning,  the  deep  roll  of 
the  thunder  gradually  dying  away  in  the  far  distance 
— all  this  furnishes  a  perfect  type  of  sublimity.  But 
perpetual  thunder  and  lightning  would  be  anything 
but  sublime. 

It  may  be  well  to  specially  note  one  element  of 
sublimity — mystery.  The  objects  of  idealistic  emo- 
tion, as  we  have  repeatedly  seen,  are  dimly  perceived; 
and  as  dimness  passes  into  mystery,  that  emotion 
rises  in  intensity.  Therefore,  mystery  promotes  the 
sense  of  sublifhity;  and  on  the  other  hand,  clearness 
is  essential  to  the  ludicrous.  The  obscurity  which 
would  be  fatal  to  the  excellence  of  a  joke,  intensifies 
the  sublime. 

Still  another  gleam  of  light  must  be  thrown  upon 
the  relation  between  the  sublime  and  the  ludicrous. 
The  sublime  we  now  know  to  be  that  which  produces 


52  SCIENCE    OF    THOUCHT. 

the  utmost  intensity  of  idealistic  emotion  delicately 
balanced  by  realistic  feeling;  and  that  evidently  must 
be  a  state  of  most  unstable  equilibrium.  In  other 
words,  it  is  a  state  extremely  liable  to  sudden  collapse. 
But  from  the  definitions  already  given,  it  is  obvious 
that*  the  sudden  collapse  of  the  sublime  would  form  a 
perfect  type  of  the  ludicrous.  This  is  the  philosophic 
explanation  of  the  proverb  that  it  is  but  a  step  from 
the  sublime  to  the  ridiculous. 

The  opposition  between  realism  and  idealism  in  art 
has  long  been  recognized:  but  only  in  a  vague,  em- 
pirical way  which  has  resulted  in  nothing  but  endless 
disputes.  But  now  for  the  first  time  these  two  tend- 
encies have  been  analyzed  and  their  respective  char- 
acteristics fully  described.  Now  also  the  exact 
relation  between  them  has  been  stated — not  of  an- 
tagonism but  of  reciprocal  need  of  each  other  in  the 
perfect  balance  of  thought.  And  thus  a  law  of  the 
beautiful  has  been  formed  whereby  we  have  been  able 
to  explain  those  aesthetic  judgments  and  principles  of 
art  which  have  heretofore  been  despairingly  re- 
garded as  ultimate,  inexplicable  facts  given  to  men  by 
some  magic  of  instinct  or  intuition.  And  this  law  of 
beauty  we  have  derived  from  a  still  wider  law,  simple 
and  universal  as  gravity. 


CHAPTER  VIII. 
PAGAN  CIVILIZATION. 

The  nature  of  thought,  then,  is  everywhere  the 
same.  All  processes  of  thinking,  from  the  simplest 
perception  up  to  the  splendors  of  physical,  moral  and 
aesthetic  science  have  one  common  characteristic  and 
obey  one  universal  law.  It  remains  now  to  show  that 
this  law  will  explain  the  course  of  human  civilization 
and  thus  give  to  us  a  true  philosophy  of  history. 

Beginning  with  ancient  civilization,  we  find  there 
two  distinct  types  of  development,  the  Oriental  and 
the  Classical.  The  first  of  these  is  ruled  by  the  ideal- 
istic impulse,  the  other  by  the  realistic:  each  thus  un- 
duly emphasizes  one  element  of  thought  and  ignores 
the  other.  And  each  thus  becomes  fatally  defective, 
because  it  is  the  development  of  a  one-sided  and  ex- 
aggerated tendency  of  the  human  spirit.  To  prove 
this  let  us  consider,  first,  the  characteristic  features 
of  Oriental  civilization. 

(i)  It  has  long  been  well  understood  that  the  pre- 
vailing philosophy  of  the  Orient  was  an  extravagant 
idealism.  For  Oriental  thought,  the  whole  visible 
universe  shrivels  into  Maya  or  illusion.  Even  per- 
sonality is  recognized  only  as  a  transient  form  of  be- 
ing, which  finally  fades  into  the  abstractness  of  Brahma 
or  the  nothmgness  of  Nirvana.  Everything  is 
sacrificed  to  the  passion  for  gazing  into  the  depths  of 
pure  existence,  the  absolute  cause,  the  unity  and  per- 


54  SCIENCE    OF   THOUGHT. 

manence  underlying  all  multiplicity  and  change.  Along 

with  this  go  all  the  minor  marks  of  an  excessive  ideal- 
ism. The  disdain  of  experience,  the  constant  appeal 
to  intuition  or  ecstacy  or  some  other  mystic,  a  priori 
process  of  thought,  the  slavish  deference  to  authority, 
the  absence  of  free  inquiry  and  of  the  critical  spirit — 
all  these  are  well  known  features  of  the  Oriental  mind. 
(2)  Oriental  religion  has  six  essential  characteris- 
tics. First  a  pantheistic  conception  of  the  universe; 
all  finite  existence  is  but  a  mode  of  the  absolute. 
Secondly,  fatalism;  human  life  is  everywhere  enmeshed 
in  the  bonds  of  an  infinite  causality.  This  is  very 
different,  however,  from  that  modern  denial  of  moral 
freedom  which  is  based  upon  the  ignoring  of  all  con- 
scious causality  whatever;  the  two  opposite  tendencies 
of  the  human  spirit  frequently  reach  the  same  abyss, 
through  different  roads.  Thirdly,  sacerdotalism;  for 
man,  a  mere  waif  of  weakness  and  sin,  there  is  no  way 
of  salvation  save  through  priestly  intervention.  Fourth- 
ly, the  sacrificial  element  overwhelms  the  moral;  man's 
weak  striving  after  righteousness  is  in  vain;  piety  con- 
sists not  in  virtue  but  in  sacrifice,  not  in  what  we  do, 
but  in  what  we  surrender  to  the  Infinite.  Fifthly,  the 
complete  subordination  of  reason  to  faith;  the  soul 
cannot  attain  to  truth  through  its  unaided  efforts,  but 
only  through  revelation  and  ecstacy.  Sixthly,  a  wild 
supernaturalism;  man  disdaining  the  present  world  of 
illusions  and  changes,  gives  himself  up  to  dreams  of 
futurity.  These  are  the  manifest  characteristics  of 
Oriental  religion;  and  they  all  are  the  evident  products 
of  that  idealistic  tendency  which  sacrifices  theindivid- 


PAGAN    CIVILIZATION.  55 

ual,  the  many  and  the  transitory,  in  order  to  lay  all 
emphasis  upon  the  thought  of  one,  unchanging  and 
eternal  cause. 

(3)  Oriental  morality  is  under  the  same  pitiless 
law  of  one-sided  development.  The  sense  of  causal- 
ity is  pushed  to  fatal  excesses.  The  feeling  of  respons- 
ibility to  the  higher  powers  forms  the  almost  exclusive 
rule  of  action.  The  practical  consequences  of  con- 
duct are  so  completely  ignored  that  the  moral  ideal  is 
made  to  consist  in  the  sacrifice  of  happiness,  in  the 
cruel  tortures  of  asceticism. 

At  the  conclusion  of  the  chapter  upon  ethics  we  have 
described  the  inevitable  results  of  a  morality  which  ig- 
nores the  consequences  of  conduct;  and  the  Orient  is  a 
living  witness  to  the  truth  of  that  description.  The 
Oriental  spirit,  weighed  down  by  the  sense  of  sin 
and  responsibility,  is  manifestly  lacking  in  moral  tone 
and  vigor.  It  is  obedient,  very  scrupulous  about  mi- 
nute things,  but  strangely  neglectful  of  the  weightier 
matters  of  the  law.  Veracity  in  the  East  seems  hardly 
to  be  numbered  among  the  virtues.  Justice  is  but  an- 
other name  for  the  whims  of  a  despot.  Benevolence, 
confining  its  care  to  bugs,  monkeys  and  other  beasts, 
has  but  slight  concern  for  the  misery  and  agony  of 
men.  In  a  word,  Oriental  morality,  vitiated  by  the 
lack  of  the  utilitarian  or  realistic  element  is  unpracti- 
cal, incoherent  and  fantastic. 

(4)  Idealism,  as  we  have  seen,  is  essentially  deduc- 
tive. The  Orient  has  consequently  made  no  slight 
contributions  to  mathematical  science,  wherein  deduc- 
tion preponderates.      But  in  physical  or  experimental 


56  SCIENCE   OF   THOUGHT, 

science  there  has  been  but  little  progress  on  account 
of  that  disdain  for  experience,  lack  of  free  inquiry  and 
the  clinging  to  the  authority  of  the  past  which  are  so 
characteristic  of  extreme  idealism. 

(5)  That  Oriental  art  is  intensly  idealistic,  probably 
no  one  will  deny.  Its  straining  after  the  sublime  in 
the  guise  of  the  colossal,  the  aspect  of  repose  and 
permanence  which  pervades  its  creation,  its  passion 
for  mystery,  for  Sphynx-like  obscurity  and  the  dim 
suggestion  of  deep  truths — all  these  we  have  seen  to 
be  the  essential  marks  of  idealistic  art.  But  it  is  ideal- 
ism in  excess.  Its  seriousness  often  sinks  into  a  dull, 
depressing  solemnity.  It  lacks  that  realistic  sense  of 
measure  and  proportion  which  comes  from  exact  ob- 
servation. It  cares  little  for  the  close  imitation  of  re- 
ality. And  thus  its  vague  and  shadowy  conceptions 
are  always  apt  to  become  painfully  grotesque. 

The  chief  triumphs  of  Oriental  art  have  been  archi- 
tectural. And  the  reason  is  now  evident.  For  arch- 
itecture, employing  the  most  rigid  materials  in  great 
masses,  and  forced  to  adapt  itself  to  utilitarian  de- 
signs, gives  less  chance  for  the  vagaries  of  an  extrav- 
agant idealism,  while  affording  full  scope  for  the  ideal- 
istic delight  in  power,  repose  and  mystery.  This  is 
the  truth  which  is  partially  and  empirically  recog- 
nized in  Hegel's  famous  formula  of  architecture  as  the 
symbolic  art  —  the  art  best  fitted  to  express  "the  ob- 
scure ideas"  of  the  Orient  and  the  Middle  Ages. 

Another  characteristic — and  a  very  noble,  although 
little  noticed  one — is  its  idealistic  love  of  Nature.     Of 


PAGAN    CIVILIZATION.  57 

this  we  shall  have  more  to  say  in  treating  of  classical 
civilization. 

(6)  Social  organization  in  the  East  is  ruled  by  the 
same  one-sided  impulse.  Its  aim  is  the  complete  sub- 
ordination of  the  many  to  the  one.  The  freedom  of 
individuals,  personal  rights  and  private  interests  are  all 
ruthlessly  sacrificed  to  the  idealistic  demand  for  power, 
unity  and  permanence  in  the  social  system.  Hence 
came  the  colossal  empires  which  once  ruled  the  East. 
Hence,  also,  the  institution  of  castes,  that  overwhelm- 
ing sacrifice  of  the  individual  to  the  universal.  And 
hence  the  peculiar  character  of  Oriental  laws,  which 
are  minute  restrictions  imposed  upon  every  detail  of 
human  conduct;  secondly,  are  divine  revelations,  as 
the  institutes  of  Menu,  for  instance,  declare;  and 
thirdly,  must  from  age  to  age  be  sacredly  preserved 
from  all  change  or  innovation.  In  the  land-laws  there 
is  even  a  communistic  tinge;  the  right  of  property 
floats  loosely  between  the  individual  holder,  the  vil- 
lage community  and  the  state.  Everywhere  the  ten- 
dency is  to  centralize;  the  centripetal  forces  completely 
over-power  the  centrifugal.  In  a  word  Oriental  so- 
ciety caring  solely  for  unity  and  permanence,  is  the  very 
incarnation  of  an  excessive  and  unbalanced  idealism. 


As  Oriental  life  was  idealistic,  so  classical  life 
was  realistic  to  excess.  This  is  the  philosophic 
formula  for  that  deep  and  wide  contrast  between  the 
two,  which  has  been  universally  recognized. 

(1)  Greek  philosophy  is  essentially  realistic.  Pla- 
tonism,  at  first  view,  seems  to  directly  contradict  this 


58  SCIENCE   OF   THOUGHT. 

statement;  but  the  genius  of  Plato  was  diametrically 
opposed  to  the  ruling  tendencies  of  classical  thought. 
That  is  proved  by  several  considerations.  First  the 
Platonic  philosophy  did  not  thrive  until  after  many 
centuries  it  was  transplanted  to  Alexandria  where 
Oriental  influences  were  supreme.  Secondly,  the 
great  master  himself  seems  to  have  been  a  somewhat 
wavering  supporter  of  his  own  principles;  in  his  later 
dialogues  there  is  an  evident  recoil  from  an  idealism 
so  repugnant  to  the  native  bent  of  the  Greek  mind. 
Thirdly,  his  absolutism  and  contempt  for  liberty,  his 
communistic  scorn  of  all  individualism,  and  above  all, 
his  disdain  for  art,  show  how  far  he  had  separated  him- 
self from  the  ruling  impulses  of  his  race.  Plato,  indeed, 
is  a  protestant  against,  rather  than  a  representative 
of  the  prevailing  tendencies  of  classical  life. 

Looking  then  at  the  entire  movement  of  Greek  and 
Roman  speculation,  we  see  that  it  became  more  and 
more  realistic  and  at  last  ended  in  thorough  skepticism. 
The  protest  of  Plato  and  his  few  followers  was  but  an 
eddy  in  the  current. 

(2)  The  realistic  impulse  engrossed  with  the  phe- 
nomenal, neglectful  of  those  higher  conceptions  which 
bind  all  things  into  unity  and  permanence,  can  give 
but  a  feeble  support  to  religion.  And  such  was  sig- 
nally the  case  in  Greek  and  Roman  history.  We  have 
there  presented  before  us  the  unique  example  of  a  re- 
ligion without  a  revelation.  The  supernatural  is  re- 
duced to  its  minimum.  The  idealistic  conception  of 
the  Infinite  is  almost  wholly  wanting;  the  gods  are 
immortal    men,  glorified    types   of   humanity,    but   as 


PAGAN    CIVILIZATION.  59 

thoroughly  finite,  especially  in  morals,  as  any  ordinary 
mortal.  Religion  became  merely  a  function  of  the 
state;  the  priests  were  simply  public  officials;  and  wor- 
ship a  beautiful  custom  to  be  maintained  in  the  inter- 
est of  law  and  order.  Under  such  condition  criticism 
and  doubt  had  an  easy  triumph.  The  simple  child- 
like piety  of  earlier  times  was  saved  from  utter  extinc- 
tion only  by  that  counter-tendency — that  idealistic  or 
causal  impulse — which,  however  repressed,  still  ob- 
scurely pervades  the  human  mind,  because  it  is  in- 
volved in  the  very  nature  of  thought. 

(3)  Classical  morality  also  was  ruled  by  the  realis- 
tic impulse.  Socrates  always  indentified  virtue  with 
wisdom;  and  from  that  thoroughly  utilitarian  view 
classical  thought — even  among  the  Platonists  and 
Stoics  —  never  departed.  There  is  hardly  a  trace  of 
that  Oriental  conception  of  virtue  as  obedience  to  im- 
mutable law  supernaturally  imposed.  The  Greek 
gods,  in  fact,  were  very  poorly  fitted  to  act  as  teach- 
ers of  morality.  The  wisdom  in  which  virtue  consisted 
was  to  be  gained  by  experience,  by  study  of  com- 
mon opinion  and  immemorial  custom,  by  free  and 
critical  inquiry  into  the  relative  worth  of  sensuous  and 
intellectual  consequences. 

The  morality  thus  attained  had  many  charms.  It  had 
hardly  a  tinge  of  the  hateful  Oriental  asceticism;  its  aim 
was  not  to  repress  but  to  educate,  not  the  ascetic  sacri- 
fice but  the  free,  artistic  development  of  human  nature. 
By  patient  processes  of  observation  and  free  inquiry, 
the  moral  code  became  clear,  precise  and  practical. 
And  there  was  imparted  to  classical  life,  for  a  time  at 


60  SCIENCE    OF    THOUGHT. 

least,  that  moral  tone  and  vigor  which  can  be  gained 
only  by  vivid  perception  of  the  consequences  of 
conduct. 

But  it  was  still  a  fatally  defective  morality.  It 
was  narrow  and  inadequate,  in  that  it  had  no  place 
for  those  virtues  of  obedience,  patience,  humility  and 
loving  sacrifice  which  form  the  nobler  half  of  human 
aspiration.  It  was  superficial  in  that  it  did  not  sat- 
isfy the  deepest  needs  of  life.  It  was  almost  a  stranger 
to  the  idealistic  sense  of  desert,  responsibility  and  guilt; 
from  the  days  of  Homer  downward,  sin  was  but  folly,  or 
a  passing  fit  of  madness.  In  a  word,  it  was  a  morality 
without. a  basis — without  any  deep  laid  conviction  of 
the  eternal  difference  between  duty  and  self-interest, 
the  right  and  the  expedient.  And  hence  it  soon  suc- 
cumbed to  the  mighty  forces  of  doubt  and  human 
passion. 

(4)  We  have  seen  in  a  previous  chapter  that  the 
progress  of  science  depends  upon  the  equilibrium  of 
the  realistic  or  inductive  and  the  idealistic  or  deduc- 
tive tendency.  Hence  realistic  Greece  and  Rome 
made  such  slight  scientific  advance.  Something 
more  was  needed  than  intellectual  ardor  and  the  acut- 
est  powers  of  observation;  great  thinkers  like  Aristotle 
for  instance,  might  go  on  forever,  scrutinising  the 
obvious  and  superficial  aspects  of  things  without  gain- 
ing-the  least  insight  into  the  hidden  laws  and  secret 
processes  of  nature.  But  at  Alexandria  the  needful 
equilibrium  of  impulses  was,  for  a  brief  period  attained. 
That  great  city,  lying  at  the  gateway  of  ancient 
commerce,  became  the  focus  of  the  Oriental  influen- 


PAGAN    CIVILIZATION.  6 1 

ces,  that  were  streaming  in  upon  the  west;  and  in  her 
schools  there  was,  for  a  time,  an  eclectic  commingling 
of  the  two  tendencies  of  the  human  spirit. 

Hence  it  happened,  just  as  our  law  would  demand, 
that  classical  science  was  almost  exclusively  Alexan- 
drian. We  need  only  point  to  the  immortal  discov- 
eries of  Hipparchus  and  Eratosthenes  in  astronomy 
and  geography,  of  Euclid  in  geometry,  and  Archimedes 
in  mechanics — to  show  how  much  was  done  for  science 
in  that  eclectic  city,  and  how  little  outside  the  circle 
of  her  influence. 

But  this  synthesis  was  purely  fortuitous  ;  it  was  the 
temporary  product  of  fortunate  but  fleeting  conditions. 
Alexandrian  idealism  soon  passed  into  the  wildest 
Oriental  mysticism  and  was  cast  aside  by  the  realistic 
common-sense  of  the  Greek  and  Roman  mind.  Hence- 
forward classical  life  went  on  in  its  own  empirical  way 
and  science  made  no  farther  progress. 

Thus  our  law  is  not  only  verified,  but  it  solves  one 
of  the  chief  enigmas  of  history — -the  failure  of  the 
acute,  inquiring  intellect  of  antiquity  to  make  any 
scientific  progress  except  under  the  Alexandrian 
influence. 

(5)  Classical  art  also  was  intensely  realistic.  It 
has,  of  course,  an  idealistic  element,  or  else  it  would 
not  have  been  genuine  art  ;  but  the  idealism  is  sup- 
pressed, suggested  rather  than  boldly  presented. 
There  is  no  taint  of  Oriental  extravagance  and  dreami- 
ness, no  straining  after  the  sublime,  the  mysterious  or 
the  profound.  Greek  art  was  content  to  imitate  real- 
ity exactly  as  it  appears  ;  with  critical  and   observant 


62  SCIENCE    OF    THOUGHT. 

gaze,  it  strove  to  see  things  in  their  true  measure  and 
proportion.  The  Orientals  failed  because  they  at- 
tempted so  much  ;  the  Greeks  succeeded  so  gloriously 
because  they  attempted  so  little. 

Our  doctrine  illumines  the  whole  history  of  classical 
art.  But  I  can  only  note  a  few  particulars.  First, 
it  explains  the  peculiar  charm  of  classical  mythology 
— the  fading  of  the  wild,  grotesque  dreams  of  the 
primitive  nature-worship  before  a  realism  which 
cared  more  for  the  correct  imitation  of  actual  life  than 
for  the  mystic  meaning  of  the  myth.  Secondly,  it 
explains  the  position  of  sculpture  as  preeminently  the 
classical  art  ;  for  that  is  the  most  imitative  of  all  the 
arts,  the  one  which  depends  most  upon  realistic  ac- 
curacy of  observation  and  least  upon  idealistic  depth 
of  thought.  Thirdly,  it  explains  the  Greek  lack  of 
that  intense,  sympathetic  feeling  for  Nature  which  is 
so  vivid  in  Oriental  poetry  and  art — that  slight  sense 
of  the  mysterious  power,  unity  and  tranquil  order  per- 
vading all  natural  phenomena.  The  Greeks  regarded 
all  natural  scenery  with  a  practical,  utilitariar  spirit, 
not  with  reverent  idealistic  love.  The  landscape 
formed  but  a  minor  feature  of  their  art.  Fourthly, 
our  doctrine  accounts  for  the  quick  decline  of  classical 
art.  The  period  of  artistic  perfection  lasted  for  not 
much  more  than  a  century,  in  those  early  Greek  times 
when  Egyptian  and  Oriental  ideas  were  making  their 
first,  strong  impression  upon  the  native  realism  of 
Greece.  But  thenceforward,  from  century  to  cen- 
tury, art  became  more  and  more  realistic — precise, 
mechanical,  imitative.  Roman  elegance  took  the 
place  of  Greek  beauty. 


PAGAN    CIVILIZATION.  63 

(6)  Classical  society  incarnates  the  realistic  im- 
pulse toward  individualism,  The  rights  of  the  indi- 
vidual were  not  sacrificed,  as  in  the  Orient,  to  the 
demand  for  social  unity  and  permanence  ;  on  the 
contrary,  they  were  made  the  supreme  consideration. 
Government,  in  theory  at  least,  was  reduced  to  its 
minimum  ;  it  existed  solely  for  the  protection  of  per- 
sonal liberty  and  private  rights. 

Classical  law  thus  became  the  exact  reverse  of 
Oriental.  First,  its  origin  was  not  revelation,  but 
human  reason  ;  it  was  the  concentrated  wisdom  and 
will  of  the  people.  Secondly,  its  object  was  not  to 
lay  minute  and  grievous  restrictions  upon  human 
life,  but  simply  to  protect  the  rights  of  the  many 
against  the  violence  of  the  few.  Thirdly,  its  form 
was  not  rigid  and  immutable  ;  without  the  Oriental 
dread  of  innovation,  it  was  continually  changing  to 
adapt  itself  to  the  varying  needs  of  human  life. 
These  characteristics — of  origin,  object  and  form — 
fully  describe  classical  law,  and  the  essence  of  them 
all  is  evidently  realistic  emphasis  upon  the  rights  of 
the   individual. 

The  intense  patriotism  of  classical  antiquity  in  its 
best  ages  can  also  be  readily  explained.  The  Greeks 
regarded  the  state  as  the  citadel  of  his  rights  and 
liberties ;  the  Oriental  regarded  it  as  an  altar  upon 
which  he  must  sacrifice  all  individual  claims  and  in- 
terest's. Obviously,  a  far  more  fervent  love  of  the 
state  would  arise  in  the  former  case  than  in  the 
latter. 


64  SCIENCE    OF    THOUGHT. 

The  social  development  thus  attained  was  for  a 
brief  period,  very  grand  and  beautiful  ;  but  it  was 
one-sided,  fatally  defective  and  doomed  to  speedy 
decline.  Among  many  proofs  of  this  I  can  note  only 
the  existence  of  slavery.  That  has  always  been  re- 
garded as  an  anomaly,  but,  in  fact,  it  was  a  natural 
and  necessary  product  of  the  classical  spirit.  The 
fierce  passions  of  an  unchecked  individualism  will 
always  reduce  the  weak  to  some  form  or  other  of 
servitude.  When  all  emphasis  is  laid  upon  rights 
rather  than  upon  duties  the  strong  will  never  doubt 
their  right  of  property  in  human  flesh. 

It  was  also  inevitable  that  the  classical  regime 
should  end  in  a  military  despotism.  For  realism  is 
purely  divisive.  No  wisdom  or  patriotism  can  long 
restrain  the  strife  of  individualism,  the  bitter  struggle 
between  the  rich  and  the  poor,  the  strong  and  the 
weak.  For  a  social  system  like  that  of  classical 
antiquity,  brute  force  is  the  only  enduring  bond  of 
union. 


CHAPTER  IX. 
CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION. 

The  law  of  Pagan  life,  then,  is  the  unchecked, 
exaggerated  development  of  one  or  the  other  of  the 
two  conflicting  impulses  of  thought.  Christian  civil- 
ization is  under  an  altogether  different  law.  Its  aim 
is  to  convert,  to  regenerate,  to  transform  the  human 
'spirit.  Finding  one  impulse  abnormally  developed 
into  fatal  excesses,  it  arouses  the  counter-impulse  of 
human  nature  ;  it  awakens  a  new  spirit,  a  new  life  to 
struggle  with  the  old,  and  thus  effects  the  intellectual 
and  moral  regeneration  of  the  race. 

Mediaeval  or  Catholic  civilization  found  itself  con- 
fronted with  a  life  thoroughly  realistic.  The  real- 
ism of  Germanic  savagery  differed  from  that  of  Latin 
culture  only  in  being  cruder  and  fiercer.  There- 
fore, according  to  our  law,  Mediaeval  Christianity 
must  seek  to  arouse  the  counter-impulse,  the  ideal- 
istic spirit;  in  a  word,  it  must  strive  to  Orientalize 
the  West.  That  it  did  so  we  shall  now  attempt  to 
prove. 

(i)  The  dominant  philosophy  of  the  middle  ages, 
despite  the  misleading  name  which  it  happened  to  as- 
sume, is  thoroughly  idealistic.  Orthodox  scholasti- 
cism, caring  little  for  the  individual,  the  phenomenal, 
ever  soars  away  into  the  super-sensuous  realm  of 
universals,  ideas,  causes.  Its  long  struggle  against 
5 


66  SCIENCE    OF   THOUGHT. 

Nominalism  was  a  battle  in  behalf  of  the  logical  prin- 
ciples which  underlie  a  true  Oriental   idealism. 

The  other  features  of  Mediaeval  thought  are  of  the 
same  idealistic  or  Oriental  cast.  Subordination  of 
reason  to  faith,  slavish  submissiveness  to  the  authority 
of  the  past,  endless  commenting  upon  ancient  works, 
delight  in  abstraction  and  in  the  spinning  of  subtile 
distinctions,  credulity,  dread  of  criticism  and  free  in- 
quiry— all  these  intellectual  traits  are  as  prominent 
in  the  middle  ages  as  in  the  Orient.  Catholic  Chris- 
tianity had  completely  transformed  the  intellectual 
life  of  Europe. 

(2)  Mediaeval  religion  is  marked  by  every  one  of 
those  six  essential  characteristics,  which  we  have 
found  in  Asiatic  faith.  In  fact,  there  are  so  many 
striking  resemblances  between  Catholicism  and  Ori- 
ental religion — especially  Buddhism — that  some  have 
thought  that  one  was  copied  from  the  other.  But 
this  is  historically  absurd.  The  two  systems  have 
so  many  points  of  similarity,  because  they  are  crea- 
tions of  the  same  idealistic  tendency. 

I  can  note  here  but  one  other  distinctive  feature  of 
Mediaeval  religion,  but  that  a  most  significant  one. 
In  the  East  religion  has  ever  been  in  harmony  with 
the  ruling  tendency  of  popular  life,  in  fact,  one  of 
the  forms  of  its  development.  But  Catholic  religion 
began  as  a  reformatory  and  regenerating  movement 
against  the  realism  that  had  ruled  the  Germanic  and 
Latin  races  ;  and  for  many  centuries  so  continued. 
Hence  came  that  long  struggle  between  the  temporal 
and  the  spiritual  power  that  forms  the   most  unique 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  67 

and  striking  feature  of  Mediaeval  history.  On  the  one 
side  was  the  Catholic  church,  that  marvelous  creation 
of  the  idealistic  craving-  after  unity  and  permanence 
—  all  its  chief  institutions,  the  hierarchy,  the  mon- 
astic discipline,  the  celibacy  of  the  clergy,  the  con- 
fessional and  the  inquisition  being  inspired  with  the 
common  design  of  repressing  individualism  and  in- 
fusing into  the  Middle  Ages  a  true  Oriental  spirit  of 
unity,  obedience  and  faith.  On  the  other  side  stood 
the  temporal  power,  the  military  class,  the  anarchy, 
first  savage  and  then  feudal,  the  heresies  and  unbe- 
lief— all  the  secularizing  forces  of  such  realism  as 
still  survived.  From  century  to  century  the  struggle 
went  on,  until  Christendom  had  been  completely 
transformed  ;  and  then  the  mission  of  the  Mediaeval 
regime  was  at  an  end. 

(3)  The  revolution  effected  in  European  morality 
was  equally  sweeping.  Classical  utilitarianism  per- 
ished utterly;  conduct  was  judged  not  by  its  prac- 
tical consequences,  but  by  its  conformity  to  a  divine 
code  upheld  by  supernatural  sanctions.  For  the 
Greeks,  the  essence  of  virtue  was  wisdom  ;  for  the 
Middle  Ages,  it  was  emotion.  Ecstasy  took  the  place 
of  reason.  The  estimate  of  different  duties  was 
exactly  reversed.  Benevolence,  which  Plato  had  not 
even  named  among  the  virtues,  rose  to  the  highest 
place  of  all ;  while  prudence,  justice  and  veracity 
sank  correspondingly  in  the  scale.  The  Asiatic  ideal 
of  ascetic  repression  was  substituted  for  the  Greek 
ideal  of  free  self-development. 

Still  the  moral  revolution  did   not   reach  to  the  full 


68  SCIENCE    OF    THOUGHT. 

height  of  Oriental  excess.  The  idealistic  impulse  was 
reacted  upon  by  the  counter-impulse  which  it  was 
subverting. 

(4)  Mediaeval  idealism,  deductive  and  averse  to  ex- 
perience, could  make  no  scientific  progress;  but  it 
furnished  the  indispensable  preparation  for  such  prog- 
ress. There  was  first  needed  an  idealistic  age  which 
should  train  the  European  intellect  to  distrust  mere 
appearances,  to  understand  that  the  inner  constitu- 
tion of  things  is  seldom  revealed  by  their  most  obvi- 
ous characteristics,  to  seek  with  unconquerable  faith 
after  the  unity  and  unchanging  order  hidden  within 
the  seeming  chaos  of  Nature.  Then  scientific  research 
became  possible.  Without  such  a  preparation,  the 
modern  age  of  free  inquiry  would  have  ended  just  as 
the  Greek  age  did,  in  crude  and  barren  empiricism. 

It  has  long  been  recognized  that  alchemy  was  a  sort 
of  forerunner  to  modern  science.  But  this  is  only  a 
dim,  empirical  recognition  of  the  law  here,  for  the 
first  time,  disclosed.  Alchemy  and  the  other  occult 
and  mystical  arts  were  but  incidents  in  that  idealistic 
development  which  ruled  the  Middle  Ages  and  pre- 
pared the  way  for  modern  science. 

(5)  The  parallelism  between  Mediaeval  and  Oriental 
art  seems  perfect  at  every  point.  In  both  architect- 
ure is  the  supreme  art,  the  one  attracting  the  greatest 
attention  and  reaching  the  highest  excellence.  In 
both  there  is  the  same  striving  after  sublimity,  an  aim 
more  fully  attained,  perhaps,  in  the  great  cathedrals 
than  in  any  other  work  of  man.  In  both  there  is  the 
same  spirituality,  depth  of  thought   and  vagueness  of 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  69 

expression  that  together  form  what  Hegel  calls  sym- 
bolic art.  In  both  there  is  a  high  degree  of  that 
idealistic  love  of  Nature  so  strangely  lacking  in  classi- 
cal art.  In  both  there  is  the  same  obscurity  which 
seeks  more  to  stimulate  the  imagination  than  to 
clearly  and  closely  imitate  reality.  The  poetry  of 
Dante  and  the  forest-like  gloom  of  a  Gothic  cathedral 
are  the  most  perfect  types  of  this  idealistic  delight  in 
dim  suggestion. 

(6)  Mediaeval  society  was  based  upon  three  prin- 
ciples. The  first  principle  was  that  of  a  true,  Oriental 
absolutism  which  must  be  understood  as  the  exact  re- 
verse of  the  military  despotism  with  which  classical 
life  ended.  The  latter  was  purely  materialistic,  the 
crushing  of  the  human  spirit  by  brute  force;  the  for- 
mer sprang  from  a  voluntary  surrender  to  the  ideal- 
istic craving  for  social  unity,  permanence  and  order. 
The  Mediaeval  regime  began  with  social  chaos.  But 
from  century  to  century  the  idealistic  desire  of  unity 
increased;  the  thought  of  a  common  language  and 
country  grew  more  potent;  the  Oriental  virtues  of 
obedience,  resignation  and  faith  or  loyalty  were  more 
firmly  woven  into  popular  life;  and  thus-  the  great 
kingdoms  of  Europe  were  founded,  not  by  force  of 
arms,  but  by  a  universal  impulse. 

The  second  organizing  principle  was  feudalism, 
which  consisted  essentially  in  the  feudal  tenures  of 
property.  These  are  obviously  the  outcome  of  an 
idealistic  sacrifice  of  rights  to  duties  and  services.  As 
in  the  Orient,  so  in  the  Middle  Ages,  a  full  right  of 
property  is  lodged  nowhere;   it  floats  about  like  a  mist 


/O  sell  \<  i.  '  >i     i  lion, in  . 

between  the  crown,  the  feudal  lord  and  the  vassal. 
The  abstract  right  was  restricted  and  belittled  in  every 

possible  way,  and  it  was  made  entirely  dependent 
upon  a  complicated  network  ot  services,  aids,  reliefs 
and  other  feudal  duties. 

In  practical  life,  the  Mediaeval  impulse  could  not  go 
farther  than  this  mere  restriction  of  the  rights  of  pro- 
perty. Hut  at  heart  idealism  is  always  communistic. 
The  great  idealists  of  antiquity,  Plato,  Pythagoras  and 
their  followers  were  all  communists.  The  same 
theory  ruled  the  higher  types  of  Oriental  religion, 
preeminently  Buddhism.  So  it  did  in  Mediaeval  re- 
ligion, which  glorified  poverty  and  felt  that  men 
really  owned  nothing  and  owed  everything.  And 
this  theory  working  darkly  upon  practical  life  as  best 
it  could,  gave  rise  to  the  feudal  tenures  so  strangely 
hemmed  round  about  by  all  manner  of  restrictions. 

The  third  social  principle  was  that  of  serfdom. 
Slavery  we  have  found  to  be  the  natural  product  of 
realistic  individualism  with  its  fierce  emphasis  upon 
the  rights  of  property.  As  these  rights  dwindled, 
slavery  perished.  But  the  freedom  thus  gained  was 
restricted  in  every  way  ;  the  serf  was  even  fixed  to 
the  soil,  and  had  no  legal  redress  against  his  lord. 
In  a  word,  serfdom  and  the  Oriental  system  of  castes 
were  of  the  same  essence  :  both  were  grievous  restric- 
tions upon  human  rights  in  the  interest  of  social  order 
and  stability. 

The  three  essential  characteristics  of  the  Mediaeval 
regime,  then,  all  have  the  same  origin.  The  idealistic 
and  Oriental  demand  for  order,  unity  and  permanence 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  7  I 

had   triumphed    over  the  old  classical   and  Germanic 
delight  in  individualism  and  change. 


The  Mediaeval  movement  had  fulfilled  its  mission. 
European  life  had  been  transformed  ;  the  West  was 
being  rapidly  converted  into  a  new  Orient.  If  the 
movement  had  gone  on  unchecked  much  longer,  abso- 
lutism, superstition  and  a  true  Oriental  torpor  would 
have  enslaved  Christendom ;  and  human  progress 
would  have  been  at  an  end. 

But  Christianity  was  true  to  its  fundamental  law  of 
regeneration.  Against  the  old  order  of  things,  there 
suddenly  rose  a  mighty  outburst  of  protest  and  reform. 
The  tendencies  of  European  life  were  reversed;  indi- 
vidualism and  progressive  change  became  the  ideals 
of  civilization.  Thus  began  that  modern  period  whose 
characteristics  we  have  now  to  describe. 

Before  going  into  details,  however,  one  general 
characteristic  must  be  noted.  Although  the  pendulum 
oscillates  from  one  side  to  the  other,  it  marks  a  con- 
tinuous, forward  movement  of  time.  The  Mediaeval 
period  formed  an  indispensable  preparation  for  the 
modern.  The  really  valuable  results  gained  in  the 
Middle  Ages  were  not  lost  ;  the  conquered  handed 
over  many  treasures  into  the  possession  of  the  con- 
querors. This  retention  of  Mediaeval  results  has  caused 
that  complexity  of  modern  life  which  every  observer 
has  noted.  It  is  a  complexity  so  great  as  might  seem 
to  render  all  analysis  impossible  ;  but  the  exceeding 
simplicity  of  our  fundamental  law  will  enable  us  to 
unravel  it  all. 


72  SCIENCE   OF  THOUGHT. 

(i)  The  complex  movement  of  modern  speculation 
can  be  reduced  to  a  very  simple  formula.  The  real- 
istic impulse  has  passed  through  four  phases  of  ever 
increasing  power;  the  idealistic  impulse  has  passed 
through  four  correspondent  phases  of  waning.  Mod- 
ern realism  began  as  a  sober  protest  against  the 
wildest  vagaries  of  the  scholastic  idealism  then  domi- 
nant. Thence  it  passed  into  the  sensationalism  of 
Locke;  then  into  the  crude  materialism  of  the 
French  Encyclopedists  ;  fourthly  and  lastly,  into  the 
abject  agnosticism  of  Mills,  Spencer  and  the  great 
mass  of  modern  thinkers.  The  realism  which  began 
as  a  modest,  reforming  impulse,  ends  as  pure  destruct- 
iveness  and  negation. 

The  four  waning  phases  of  modern  idealism  are  as 
follows:  It  began  as  an  ontological  idealism,  thorough- 
going and  mystical,  which  had  been  inherited  from  the 
middle  ages.  The  second  period  was  ushered  in  by 
Descartes  and  Leibnitz,  who  gave  up  the  ontologic 
basis  for  a  merely  psychologic  one,  confining  them- 
selves to  the  defense  of  ''innate  ideas,"  or  "intui- 
tions," or  "universal  and  necessary  truths."  Kant 
introduces  the  third  period,  teaching  a  merely  ethical 
idealism  founded  upon  certain  postulates  assumed  by 
"the  practical  reason,"  because  they  are  supposed  to 
be  morally  useful.  In  the  fourth  period,  the  ethical 
basis  has  been  given  up  and  idealism  has  become 
purely  imaginative.  This  final  phase  is  represented 
in  England  by  Hamilton,  whose  doctrine  is  based 
upon  "the  impotence  of  thought";  in  France,  by 
Cousin,  who  rests   everything    upon  "the  spontaneity 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  73 

of  reason" — that  is  upon  an  unreflective  and  therefore 
unreasoning  reason  ;  and  in  Germany  by  Hegel  whose 
idealism  is  founded  upon  the  amazing  fancy  that  con- 
tradictories are  identical. 

This  sketch  of  modern  philosophy  compresses  into 
a  page  what  might  have  well  been  expanded  into  a 
volume;  but  its  truthfulness  cannot  be  successfully 
impugned.  How  utterly  idealism  has  waned  before 
the  counter-impulse  is  further  proved,  firstly,  by  the 
extreme  smallness  of  the  remnant  who  adhere  to  the 
doctrine;  secondly,  by  the  character  of  the  practical 
conclusions  finally  attained,  which  do  not  seem  to  be 
essentially  different  from  those  of  the  rankest  realism. 
But  still  let  us  give  all  honor  to  the  genius  of  these 
great  German  thinkers — to  Hegel  especially,  who 
dimly  discerned  the  essential  duality  of  thought,  al- 
though rather  as  a  dark  prophet  than  as  a  discoverer. 

(2)  It  is  a  mere  common  place  to  say  that  modern 
morality  is  intensely  realistic  or  utilitarian.  True, 
we  have  not  wholly  reverted  to  the  naive  child-like 
egoism  of  classical  antiquity:  our  souls  still  respond, 
at  least  faintly,  to  the  more  spiritual  influences  which 
have  survived  from  the  Middle  Ages.  In  fact,  we 
seem  to  have  two  ethical  codes — an  idealistic  doctrine  of 
self-sacrifice,  humility  and  resignation  which  we  pro- 
fess, and  a  realistic  doctrine  of  self-interest  and  indi- 
vidualism which  we  actually  practice.  But  it  is  to  be 
feared  that  our  sentimental  professions  serve  only  to 
blind  us  to  the  mighty  power  with  which  the  utili- 
tarian morality  rules  over  our  modern  life. 

(3)  Modern    religion   began   as   a  splendid    protest 


74  SCIENCE    OF   THOUGHT. 

of  individualism  and  realistic  good-sense  against 
mediaeval  priest-craft  and  superstition.  The  mag- 
nificent results  achieved  by  this  reformatory  and  re- 
generating movement  are  too  familiar  to  need  recount- 
ing here.  Still,  this  realistic  development  was  one- 
sided and  long  ago  passed  into  fatal  excesses.  The 
old  ideals  of  unity,  obedience  and  reposeful  faith  have 
departed,  although  their  shadows  yet  linger  with  us. 
The  old  content  of  religion — revelation,  sacrifice,  the 
supernatural — has  gradually  dissolved.  Nothing  ap- 
pears to  remain  but  the  erotic  element — the  one  word, 
love,  which  means  anything  from  the  spiritually  sub- 
lime to  the  sensuously  low.  In  a  word  we  are  draw- 
ing closer  and  closer  to  a  secularism,  like  that  of 
classical  antiquity,  wherein  religion  still  survives  as 
a  sentiment  and  a  social  institution,  but  without 
depth  or  intensity  of  faith  in  spiritual  things. 

In  the  Middle  Ages,  morality  was  but  a  phase  of 
religion:  but  we  have  completely  reversed  this,  and 
reduced  religion  to  a  mere  phase  of  the  ethical. 
Piety,  with  us,  is  our  utilitarian  morality  tinged  with 
emotion.  It  is  as  a  setting  sun  diffusing  its  radiance 
over  those  western  clouds  which  after  all  are  naught 
but  the  cold  gray  mists  of  approaching  night. 

(4)  Out  of  the  torpor  of  the  Middle  Ages,  a  new 
era  of  free  inquiry,  intensely  practical  and  realistic, 
suddenly  burst  upon  the  world;  and  modern  science 
began  its  swift  progress.  But  mediaeval  idealism 
with  its  deep  distrust  of  the  phenomenal  and  its  faith 
in  the  cosmic  order  hidden  beneath  the  surface  of 
things,    furnished   the    indispensable   preparation   for 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  7$ 

this  scientific  advance.  The  founders  of  science, 
Copernicus,  Kepler,  Galileo,  Descartes  and  Newton, 
were  all  idealists — men  who  retained  the  best  of  the 
past  while  yielding  themselves  to  the  new  spirit  of 
free  inquiry  and  observation.  And  ever  since  all  the 
great  scientific  discoverers,  unconsciously — or  rather, 
through  that  instinct  of  genius  which  always  shuns 
extremes  and  one-sidedness — have  exemplified  the 
law  that  scientific  progress  depends  upon  the  har- 
mony of  the  two  conflicting  tendencies  of  thought. 

This  law  also  explains  the  retardation  of  the  scien- 
tific movement.  The  grandest  triumphs  of  that  move- 
ment, as  every  one  knows,  were  gained  ir  the  first  cen- 
tury of  the  modern  era,  while  the  influences  of  idealism 
were  fresh  and  vivid.  Ever  since,  as  realism  has  in- 
creased, the  rate  of  progress  has  been  less  and  less. 
At  present  the  age  of  scientific  discovery  has  given 
way  to  one  of  mere  mechanical  invention.  The  pure- 
ly empirical  part  of  scientific  work  goes  bravely  on; 
the  great  mass  of  facts  collected  by  patient  observers, 
constantly  grows  vaster  and  more  chaotic.  But  the 
further  progress  of  true  science  depends  upon  a  new 
out-burst  of  idealistic  genius  which  shall  reduce  this 
chaos  to  the  unity  and  order  of  universal  law. 

(5)  Just  as  oursesthetic  theory  would  demand,  Chris- 
tian art  culminated  in  that  period  of  transition  when 
mediaeval  influences  werestill  strongbut  werebeingper- 
vaded  and  modified  by  the  modern  spirit.  And  ever 
since,  as  realism  has  increased,  art  has  declined.  Every 
one  knows,  for  instance,  that  in  this  period  of  transi- 
tion, painting  and   sculpture   became    more  sensuous, 


j6  SCIENCE   OF   THOUGHT. 

exactly  imitative  and  classical;  and  what  an  incom- 
parable splendor  was  thus  imparted  to  the  works  of  a 
Michel  Angelo  or  a  Raphael.  Hut  subsequent  centuries 
have  shown  that  this  splendor  was  that  of  decay,  the 
beauty  of  autumnal  leaves,  the  soft  hue  of  roses  with 
which  consumption  at  first  tinges  the  cheek  of  its  vic- 
tim. 

At  the  close  of  this  age  of  transition  when  night  and 
day  intermingled,  stood  Shakespeare,  the  crowned 
head  of  all  human  art.  Since  then  there  has  been 
idealism  in  art  and  life,  but  it  has  assumed  a  peculiar 
form.  It  has  become  purely  emotional;  driven  from 
the  field  of  thought,  it  has  found  refuge  in  that  of  feel- 
ing. 

And  herein  lies  the  explanation  of  what  is  univer- 
sally recognized  as  the  chief  characteristic  of  the  modern 
mind — that  passion  for  introspection  of  which  the  mad 
Hamlet  was  the  wonderful  prophesy.  For  all  this  pain- 
ful brooding  over  the  inner  life  is  the  evident  result  of 
that  pitiable  conflict  between  feeling  and  thought — 
between  what  men  fondly  dream  of  and  what  they 
really  believe  in.  And  out  of  this  comes  that  lack  of 
repose,  that  fever  of  unrest  and  discontent  so  percept- 
ible in  all  our  art  and  life. 

Music,  alone  of  all  the  Fine  Arts,  has  made  a  glori- 
ous advance  in  the  past  two  centuries;  and  the  explan- 
ation thereof  is  now  easy.  For  music  is  the  most  sens- 
uous of  the  arts;  it  appeals  to  feeling  rather  than  to 
thought;  its  office  is  to  stimulate  vague,  although  ex- 
alted emotion,  rather  than  to  express  definite  ideas. 
Therefore,    it   is    an  art   peculiarly    enchanting  to   an 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  TJ 

age  in  which,  as  we  have  just  seen,  the  lingering 
remnants  of  idealism  are  emotional  rather  than  intel- 
lectual. 

Other  causes  have  aided  the  triumph  of  music,  such 
as  the  great  improvement  of  musical  instruments  in  an 
inventive  and  mechanical  age.  But  the  cause  given 
above  is  the  primary  and  comprehensive  one. 

The  supremacy  of  the  novel  in  modern  literature 
can  also  be  now  readily  explained.  For  the  very  name, 
novel,  is  suggestive  of  the  realistic  element  in  art — 
of  the  delight  in  novelty,  in  variety  of  incidents,  in 
mimicry  of  real  life,  in  that  restless  play  of  '  'fancy  which 
loves  to  follow  a  long  chain  of  circumstances  from  link 
to  link." 

Another  chief  characteristic  of  the  age  is  what  a 
great  critic  calls  "its  mean  and  shallow  love  of  jest 
and  jeer;"  and  this  is  easily  accounted  for,  by  recall- 
ing our  definition  of  the  ludicrous.  The  passion  for 
comicality  is  especially  wide-spread  in  America,  the 
most  realistic  of  all  countries.  Burlesque  and  horse- 
play abound;  but  there  can  be  no  humor  where  there 
is  no  idealism. 

(6)  Our  social  life  also  has  been  completely  trans- 
formed. The  devotion  to  secular  interests,  the  fierce 
assertion  of  rights  rather  than  duties,  the  passion  for 
liberty,  the  ever  changing  whirlwind  of  innovations — 
all  these  are  the  familiar  characteristics  of  the  classi- 
cal spirit  returned  to  earth  again. 

Leaving  the  reader  to  pursue  this  plain  parallelism 
between  the  classical  and  the  modern  age,  I  shall  dwell 
only  upon  what  is  at  once   the  most    conspicuous   and 


yS  SCIENCE   OF   THOUGHT. 

the  most  unique  feature  of  our  social  life.      I  mean,  of 

course-,  that  great  industrial  movement  which  has 
brought  such  incalculable  benefits  to  mankind.  I  [ardly 
any  one  will  claim  that  the  origin  of  this  movement 
has  ever  been  satisfactorily  explained;  and  it  our  doc- 
trine is  found  to  lull)  account  lor  the  mysterious  dawn 
and  the  swift  noon-tide:  glory  of  modern  industry,  we 
may  consider  our  work  as  triumphantly  ended. 

The  first  great  characteristic  of  modern  industry  is 
its  motive.  The  love  of  wealth  is,  of  course,  natural 
to  man;  but  only  as  one  among  many  impulses.  And 
the  aim  of  the  Middle  Ages  was  to  reduce  this  pas- 
sion to  its  minimum,  by  glorifying  poverty  and  teach- 
ing men  to  despise  the  fleeting  and  illusory  vanities 
of  earth.  It  is  the  same  in  the  Orient  where  Brahmin 
beggars  or  the  mendicant  monks  of  Buddhism  stand 
at  the  summit  of  the  social  scale.  Hut  modern  real- 
ism, sensuous,  utilitarian,  lias  cast  aside  these  ascetic 
ideas;  it  has  developed  the  sordid  passion  into  a  mad- 
ness burning  in  the  very  bones  of  mankind. 

But  why,  it  may  be  asked,  did  not  the  same  spirit 
in  antiquity  attain  to  the  same  results?  Because  slav- 
ery rendered  a  true  industrial  system  impossible;  and 
therefore  classical  energy  could  find  no  outlet  save  in 
military  life,  plunder  and  prodigality.  But  since  the 
mediaeval  abolition  of  slavery,  the  economic  impulse 
has  had  full  room  to  run  its  course  unchecked.  In 
the  singleness,  the  intensity  and  the  ever  increasing 
power  of  its  motive;  the  modern  industrial  system  is 
unlike  any  other  social  system  ever  founded  upon  the 
earth. 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  79 

Mechanical  invention  has  been  a  second  great  factor 
in  the  industrial  movement.  A  realistic  age,  unhamp- 
ered by  slavery,  is  experimental,  inductive,  inventive; 
it*cares  little  for  general  principles  and  looks  only  to 
results.  Mechanical  genius  abounds.  And  so  by 
continued  experiment,  by  minute  attention  to  details 
and  successive  adaptation  of  means  to  a  desired  end, 
those  wonder-working  machines  have  been  invented, 
which  form  the  very  bone  and  sinew  of  the  industrial 
system. 

A  third  factor  is  specialization;  and  this  has  two 
causes.  In  the  first  place,  realism  attends  minutely 
to  details  and  has  an  antipathy  to  everything  wide  and 
comprehensive;  in  the  second  place,  it  fosters  indi- 
vidualism, cuts  away  the  restrictions  of  law,  or  custom 
or  caste,  and  leaves  men  free  to  follow  their  special 
aptitudes. 

Fourthly,  there  is  an  ethical  factor  which  has  entered 
largely  into  industrial  progress.  As  we  have  seen, 
realism  tends  to  foster  the  practical  virtues  at  the  ex- 
pense of  the  religious  ones.  And  it  was  this  develop- 
ment of  such  homely  virtues  as  prudence,  veracity  and 
justice,  that  has  rendered  possible  that  vast  and  com- 
plicated system  of  credit  so  essential  to  modern  industry. 
It  is  strange  to  see  how  minutely  historians  have 
described  the  rise  of  this  system  in  its  external  features, 
without  giving  the  slightest  thought  to  the  moral 
causes  upon  which  it  depends. 

A  fifth  factor  is  liberty.  Every  one  knows  how 
much  industrial  progress  owes  to  the  removal  of  re- 
strictions   like  the  mediaeval  prohibition  of  usury,  for 


80  SCIENCE   OF   THOUGHT. 

instance.  It  is  a  movement  which  appears  to  prosper 
most  when  regulated  least. 

Such  then  is  the  philosophy  of  the  industrial  move- 
ment; in  its  every  part  it  is  seen  to  be  a  product  of 
the  realism  which  rules  modern  civilization.  Observe 
furthermore  how  signally  our  law  of  exaggerated  ten- 
dencies is  verified  here  as  everywhere.  Each  of  these 
industrial  factors,  after  having  so  grandly  benefited 
mankind,  has  developed  into  fatal  excesses  —  the 
greed  of  gain  which  tortures  mankind,  the  mechanical 
habit  which  stunts  the  nobler  energies  of  the  soul,  the 
division  of  labor  which  converts  men  into  machines, 
the  cold,  calm  morality  of  self-interest  which  is  prov- 
ing to  be  a  very  Vesuvius  of  stony  vices  and  red- 
hot  passions.  See,  above  all,  how  the  passion  for 
liberty,  the  struggle  of  individualism  for  its  rights,  has 
ended  just  as  it  did  in  antiquity,  in  industrial  servi- 
tude—  in  a  tyranny  which  does  not  beat  or  behead 
the  unsubmissive,  but  merely  starves  them  and  their 
families.  In  a  word,  the  stream  of  tendency  which 
once  enriched  and  rejoiced  the  earth  has  become  a 
destroying  flood. 

The  whole  world  awaits  a  change.  Everywhere 
there  is  the  presage  of  a  new  reformatory  movement 
which  shall  check  this  evil  development  and  open  up 
new  paths  of  progress.  And  in  this  universal  expect- 
ancy is  the  final  and  supreme  verification  of  our  doc- 
trine. For  all  genuine  philosophy  is  but  the  scientific 
expression  of  what  is  vaguely  felt  by  the  common 
sense  of  mankind. 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  8 1 


CONCLUSION 


All  science  involves  a  certain  degree  of  prevision. 
We  have  discovered  the  law  of  human  progress:  and, 
beyond  all  doubt,  that  law  will  rule  so  long  as  prog- 
ress continues.  Every  detail  of  our  previous  study 
has  helped  to  demonstrate  that  the  realistic  impulse 
can  lead  henceforth  to  naught  but  evil;  and  therefore, 
the  counter  impulse  must  become  supreme  and  begin 
its  regenerating  work.  Not,  by  any  means,  that  we 
will  return  to  the  dreams  and  torpor  of  the  Middle 
Ages;  humanity  is  not  about  to  pass  into  a  period  of 
*  'second  childhood."  But  the  idealistic  impulse, 
taught  and  chastened  by  the  past,  will  once  more  hold 
sway  over  the  human  spirit.  The  search  and  rever- 
ence for  causes  will  take  the  place  of  our  present  en- 
grossment with  the  superficial,  the  multifarious  and 
the  transitory. 

Let  us  see,  so  far  as  our  narrow  limits  and  the 
complexity  of  the  phenomena  to  be  investigated  will 
permit,  what  the  law  of  civilization  promises  for  the 
future. 

In  religion  we  shall  have  a  new  age  of  faith.  But 
let  me  not  be  misunderstood:  faith  is  not  credulity  or 
superstition.  Nor  is  it  the  foe  or  even  the  rival  of 
reason;  the  past  antagonisms  between  the  two  have 
been  engendered  by  mental  one-sidedness  and  lack  of 
balance.  Faith  is  a  moral  impulse  whose  office  it  is 
to  preserve  the  equipoise  of  the  reason.  For,  the  hu- 
man soul,  weighed  down  by  its  connection  with  the 
body  and  the  passions  thereof,  is  ever  inclined  to  take 
6 


82  SCIEN4  i:   OF  THOUGHT. 

the  more  superficial  and  sensuous  view  of  things;  and 
therefore  there  is  always  need  of  a  certain  moral  ef- 
fort to  keep  the  reason  balanced  and  leave  it  free  tor 
its  highest  work  —  tlic  devout  search  for  causes  and 
eternal  unity  and  order.  True  faith,  then,  is  never 
the  enemy  of  reason  or  does  any  violence  to  it;  any 
more  than  one  does  violence  to  a  bird  when  he  opens 
her  cage  and  lets  her  forth  to  sing  and  soar. 

Superstition  is  a  disease  of  faith.  But  normal  faith 
is  ever  the  cause oi  free  inquiry.  It  was  the  idealistic 
faith  of  Copernicus  and  Kepler  that  led  them  to  their 
great  discoveries.  ]  And  above  all,  he  who  does  not 
take  pains  to  keep  his  reason  unclouded  by  sensuous- 
ness,  will  never  have  any  deep  interest  or  think  wor- 
thily concerning  spiritual  things. 

A  great  moral  regeneration  is  also  impending.  The 
ethics  of  duty  and  self-sacrifice  will  no  longer  be  a 
mere  sentiment,  a  pious  profession  :  they  will  become 
the  real  standard  of  human  conduct.  Not  that 
Comte's  wild  dream  of  altruism  will  ever  be  realized. 
Human  nature  will  never  be  so  transformed  that  men 
will  live  for  others  rather  than  for  themselves  ;  so 
stupendous  a  miracle  is  neither  to  be  expected  nor  de- 
sired.     But   the    incoming  of   idealism  will   gradually 

(x)  Copernicus  expressly  avowed  his  obligations  to  the  Pythagorean 
idealism.     See  De  Revolutionibus  Orbium  Celestium.  Lib.  i ,  Cp  j  et  8. 

He  was  constantly  inspired  by  his  idealistic  faith  in  the  symmetry  of 
the  universe  and  the  harmony  of  the  celestial  motions.  So  also  Kep- 
ler, as  see  Forster.  Kepler  und  die  H<irmo>iie  </er  Spharen,  j.  Frisch 
in  his  edition  says,  "nam  per  haec  studia  immortalem  suam  tertiam 
"legem  invenit  quae  proportiones  illas  simplicissime  exprimit  et  New- 
"tonii  de  gravitatione  doctrinae  quasi  fundamentum  putandaest." 
{A'ep/eri  Opera,  Tom.   VIII,  p.  ioij.) 


CHRISTIAN    CIVILIZATION.  83 

close  the  present  chasm  between  the  law  of  self-sacri- 
fice and  that  of  self-interest.  It  will  do  so  in  three 
ways:  first,  it  will  teach  men  that  even  the  present 
antagonism  between  the  two  principles  is  not  so  great 
as  it  superficially  seems;  that  even  now  obedience  to  the 
universal  law,  —  "the  golden  rule" — tends  to  promote 
the  happiness  of  the  individual,  although  too  often  this 
result  fails  through  the  interference  of  other  causes. 
Secondly,  it  will  weaken  the  sensuous  motives  and 
vastly  strengthen  the  idealistic  ones — the  power  of 
conscience  and  of  the  religious  and  social  sentiments 
— and  thus  make  self-sacrifice  far  more  conducive  to 
individual  happiness.  Thirdly,  it  will  strive  to  so  re- 
organize society  that  every  man  shall  enjoy  the  reward 
of  his  own  labors,  that  millions  shall  not  bear  the  bur- 
dens in  order  that  a  few  may  reap  the  benefits.  In 
that  ideal  state,  the  old  contradiction  between  duty 
and  self-interest  will  have  vanished,  virtue  and  hap- 
piness will  be  harmonized  ;  and  the  moral  order  of 
the  universe  will  seem  to  all  something  more  than  an 
idle  dream. 

Art,  in  its  present  estate,  can  well  afford  to  wel- 
come any  change — especially  a  change  from  mere  play 
and  mimicry  to  seriousness,  imaginative  power  and 
depth  of  thought.  Science,  also,  as  we  have  already 
seen,  stands  in  great  need  of  a  new  out-burst  of 
idealism. 

The  character  of  the  social  regeneration  to  come 
has  been  foreshadowed  in  our  previous  survey.  The 
trend  of  idealism,  in  the  Orient,  the  Middle  Ages, 
and    the   speculations   of    philosophy,  has    ever    been 


S..|  SCIENCE    OF  THOUGHT. 

towards  solidarity,  community  of  interests,  the  subor- 
dination <>1  rights  tO  duties,  service,  sacrifice.  Its 
very  aim  is  to  unify  or  organize.  And  its  triumph 
must    inevitably  lead  us  from  an  age  of  individualism 

to  one  of  social  and  industrial  organization. 

Hut  let  us  remember  that  organization  is  not  interfer- 
ence or  restriction  or  suppression  ;  it  is  not  a  pr< 
from  without  compacting  the  many  into  one  unre- 
sisting mass.  It  is  a  force  acting  from  within  ;  and  so 
far  from  interfering  with,  it  is  the  cause  of  the  diver- 
sity, the  changing  activity  and  the  freedom  of  the 
parts.  To  this  ideal  the  coming  organization  of 
industry  will  strictly  conform.  Every  member  of  the 
industrial  order  will  take  part  in  the  administration 
of  its  affairs,  and  all  will  cooperate  towards  its  com- 
mon ends  ;  and  the  world-wide  unity  and  regulated 
concert  of  action  thus  attained  will  produce  a  fuller 
liberty  and  a  more  joyous  activity  than  human  toil, 
heretofore,  has  ever  dreamed  of. 

These  are  but  hints  and  vague  outlines.  The 
utmost  power  of  the  scientific  imagination,  even  when 
guided  by  our  demonstrated  law,  can  do  little  more 
than  to  dream  about  the  possibilities  which  are  now 
beginning  to  open  before  mankind.  This  new  age  of 
faith,  sacrifice  and  social  order  is  like  that  new  world 
which  was  first  seen,  just  four  hundred  years  ag( 
a  little  island  in  the  ocean,  and  which  even  yet  has 
not  disclosed  the  full  extent  of  its  treasures  and  its 
promise. 

[THE    END.] 


^56 


LIBRARY    OF   CONGRESS 


II 

0  029  798  068  3