Skip to main content

Full text of "The Journal of philosophy"

See other formats


UNIV.  OF 

TOROKTO 
llBRARV 


•  mi 


mm 


RB  !H 


in  mil 


t 


BINDING  LIST  JUN  1     1923 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


s 

()&\ 

I 


THE  JOURNAL 

OF 

PHILOSOPHY 


EDITED    BY 

FREDERICK  J.  E.  WOODBRIDGE 

AND 

WENDELL  T.  BUSH 


VOLUME  XIX 

JANUARY— DECEMBER,   1922 


1922 


6 


p*cts  or 

TMC  NIW  f  HA  PRINTING  COMPANY 
LANOSTIM.  PA. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  1.  JANUARY  5,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


PRAGMATISM  AND  THE  NEW  MATERIALISM 

THE  most  striking  and  significant  phenomenon  in  recent  Ameri- 
can philosophy  and  psychology  has,  manifestly,  been  an 
extensive  recrudescence  of  materialism.  To  or  towards  this  out- 
come have  converged  several  theories  diverse  in  name  and,  in  part, 
in  the  logical  considerations  which  have  given  rise  to  them.  The 
tendency  finds  its  most  unequivocal  expression  in  behaviorism,  when- 
ever behaviorism,  as  in  the  recent  writings  of  Professor  J.  B.  Wat- 
son, abandons  the  modest  status  of  a  special  subdivision  of  psycho- 
biology,  and  sets  itself  up  as — or  as  a  substitute  for — a  general 
psychological  theory.  To  say  that  in  the  processes  commonly  known 
as  sensation,  feeling  and  thought  nothing  whatever  occurs,  or  need 
be  presupposed,  except  gross  or  microscopic  movements  of  various 
portions  of  the  musculature  of  an  organism,  is  obviously  equivalent 
to  the  reduction  of  the  entire  content  and  implications  of  experi- 
ence to  motions  of  matter  and  transfers  of  physical  energy.  In 
many  of  the  American  forms  of  neo-realism  a  scarcely  less  thorough- 
going materialism  has  been  manifest,  so  far  as  the  world  of  con- 
crete existence  is  concerned ;  though  the  tendency  here  has  been 
curiously  conjoined  with  a  revival  of  a  species — a  very  unplatonic 
species — of  "Platonic  realism."  In  most  of  our  neo-realists,  the 
latter  seems  an  essentially  otiose  addition  to  their  doctrine.  Uni- 
versals  are  asserted  to  "subsist"  merely;  and  though  subsistence 
is  declared  to  be  a  status  independent  of  consciousness,  this  inde- 
pendence renders  it  only  the  more  alien  to  nature  and  irrelevant 
to  experience.  Since  mere  subsistents  have  neither  date,  nor  place, 
nor  causal  efficacy,  they  are  pertinent  to  the  phenomenal  order  only 
in  so  far  as  they  are  embodied  in  particular  existences ;  and  by  the 
neo-realist  their  embodiment  is  apparently  construed  in  the  literal 
sense  of  the  word.  For  him  too  the  only  entities  existing  in  time 
and  in  the  causal  nexus  are  physical  masses,  and — if  the  two  be 
ultimately  distinct — physical  energy. 

American  pragmatism  has  often  manifested  a  disposition  to 
join  forces  with  behaviorism  and  neo-realism  in  their  campaign 
against  the  belief  in  the  reality  of  psychical  entities;  indeed,  if 
certain  utterances  of  its  spokesmen  be  considered  separately — apart 

5 


»i  THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

from  certain  other  utterances  which  to  the  uninitiated  appear 
simply  to  contradict  them  —  no  contemporary  philosophical  school 
has  given  plainer  expression  to  the  materialistic  doctrine.  In 
some  recent  papers  in  this  JOURNAL*  I  cited  several  instances  of 
this  ^nrt  ;  one  of  them  it  is  pertinent  to  repeat  here: 


A  careful  inventory  of  our  a**ets  brings  to  light  no  such  entities  as  those 
which  have  been  placed  to  our  credit.  We  do  not  find  body  and  object  and  con- 
faeiousness,  but  only  body  and  object.  .  .  .  The  process  of  intelligence  is  some- 
thing that  goes  on,  not  in  our  mind,  but  in  things.  .  .  .  Even  abstract  ideas  do 
not  compel  the  adoption  of  a  peculiarly  "  spiritual  "  or  "  psychic  "  existence, 
in  the  form  of  unanalyzable  meanings.* 

In  the  papers  mentioned  I  attempted  to  show,  among  other 
things,  that  this  materialistic  strain  is  incongruous  with  the  most 
characteristic  and  essential  thesis  of  pragmatism,  at  least  in  its 
later  formulations.  That  thesis  is  to  the  effect  that  "intelligence" 
is  efficacious  and  "creative."  By  "intelligence"  the  pragmatist 
appears  to  mean  nothing  mysterious  or  metaphysical;  the  word  is 
for  him  merely  a  name  for  a  familiar  type  of  experience,  that, 
namely,  of  practical  reflection,  of  forming  plans  of  action  for  deal- 
ing with  specific  concrete  situations.  This  process  of  reflection  is, 
he  maintains,  in  certain  cases  a  determinant  of  motions  of  matter, 
i.e.,  of  the  movements  of  human  bodies  and  of  other  masses  with 
which  they  physically  interact.  But  upon  the  materialistic  hypo- 
thesis practical  reflection  itself  is  nothing  but  a  motion  of  matter; 
if  "bodies  and  (physical)  objects"  are  the  only  factors  involved 
in  "intelligence,"  it  should  be  possible  to  describe  the  phenome- 
non called  "planning"  wholly  in  physical  terms  —  i.e.,  in  terms  of 
masses  actually  existing,  of  positions  actually  occupied,  of  molar 
or  molecular  movements  actually  occurring,  at  the  time  when  the 
planning  is  taking  place.  The  laws  of  that  class  of  physical  proc- 
esses called  "practical  judgments"  may,  of  course,  be  unique,  in- 
capable of  reduction  to  the  laws  of  physics  or  chemistry;  and 
pragmatism  declares  that  they  are  in  fact  thus  unique  and  irredu- 
cible. But  the  things  whose  behavior  these  laws  describe  must  —  if 
the  pragmatist  is  to  avoid  psychophysical  dualism  —  consist  solely 
of  real  parts  of  the  material  world. 

Now  since  "intelligence,"  in  the  pragmatist  's  sense,  is  an  ob- 
servable and  analyzable  phenomenon,  the  question  whether  any 
entities  are  involved  in  it  which  are  not  real  parts  of  the  material 
world  is  a  question  of  empirical  fact,  to  be  settled  by  analysis  of 
the  specific  type  of  experience  under  consideration.  And  in  my 
previous  papers  I  sought  to  show  that  this  question  must  be  answered 

i  Vol.  XVH,  pp.  589-596  and  622-632,  1920. 

*  Professor  B.  H.  Bode,  in  Creative  Intelligence,  pp.  254-5,  245. 


PRAGMATISM  AND  THE  NEW  MATERIALISM          7 

in  the  affirmative.  A  plan  of  action,  as  I  pointed  out,  obviously 
requires  the  presentation  of  both  past  and  possible  future  states 
or  contents  of  some  part  of  the  material  world.  But  a  past  or 
possible  future  state  of  the  material  world  is  not,  at  the  moment 
at  which  it  is  represented  in  the  experience  of  the  planner,  a  part 
of  the  real  material  world.  The  content  of  my  memories  or  of  my 
expectations,  as  such,  would  find  no  place  in  any  inventory  of 
then  existing  "bodies  and  objects"  which  would  be  drawn  up 
even  by  a  perfected  physical  science.  It  is  of  the  very  essence  of 
the  planning-experience  that  it  is  cognizant  of  and  concerned  with 
things,  or  configurations  of  things,  which  have  yet  to  be  physically 
realized,  and  are  therefore  not  yet  physically  real.  Thus  in  fixing 
his  attention  especially  upon  "intelligence"  in  its  practical  aspect, 
the  pragmatist  is  brought  face  to  face  with  that  type  of  experience 
in  which  the  empirical  presence  of  non-physical  entities  and  proc- 
esses is,  perhaps,  more  plainly  evident  than  in  any  other. 

This  fact,  it  may  be  remarked  parenthetically,  is  the  reason  why 
I  have  thought  it  useful  to  select  pragmatism  as  the  immediate 
point  of  attack  in  a  critical  examination  of  the  new  materialism  in 
general.  The  pragmatists  have  rendered  a  service  to  philosophers 
of  all  schools  by  directing  attention  to  the  significance  of  certain 
undeniably  real  aspects  of  the  cognitive  experience,  which  happen 
also  to  be  the  best  possible  touchstone  for  the  determination  of  the 
issue  between  those  who  assert  and  those  who  deny  the  existence 
of  psychical  or  immaterial  entities.  That  issue  has  hitherto  been 
discussed  mainly  in  connection  with  the  problem  of  perception ; 
with  that  problem,  in  fact,  the  neo-realists  seem  to  have  been  some- 
what obsessed.  The  believer  in  the  presence  of  distinctively  mental 
factors  in  the  cognitive  situation  has  not  failed  to  meet  the  issue 
on  this  the  favorite  ground  of  his  adversary.  But  in  this  part  of 
the  field  the  controversy,  if  not  logically  indecisive,  has  at  any 
rate  grown  somewhat  tedious  and  repetitious.  There  remains,  mean- 
while, a  region  of  experience  in  which  the  dispute  seems  capable 
of  being  brought  more  speedily  to  a  decisive  conclusion;  and  it  is 
with  this  region  that  the  pragmatist  is  especially  preoccupied.  He 
is  primarily  interested,  not  in  the  question  how  we  can  know  an 
external,  coexistent  object,  but  in  the  question  how  one  moment 
of  experience  can  know  and  prepare  for  another  moment.  It  is, 
in  short,  to  what  I  have  elsewhere  named  intertemporal  cognitions 
that  his  analysis  is  devoted;  it  is  by  man's  habit  of  looking  before 
and  after  that  he  is  chiefly  impressed.  Now  to  look  before  and 
after  is — as  my  previous  papers  pointed  out — to  behold  the  physi- 
cally non-existent;  it  is  to  possess  as  data  in  experience  objects 


8  THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

which  can  not  be  conceived  t<>  b»>  simultaneously  present  in  the 
material  universe.  Since,  moreover,  the  pragmatist  affirms  the 
potency  of  intelligence,  that  is  to  say,  of  this  function  of  foresight 
and  recall,  in  the  causation  of  (some)  physical  events,  his  phi- 
losophy, if  consistently  worked  out,  should  lead  him  to  an  inter- 
action ist  view  upon  the  psychophysical  problem. 

Such,  in  brief,  was  the  argument  previously  set  forth.  To  that 
argument  Professor  Bode  has  very  courteously  replied  in  an  article 
in  tliis  .lontNAL.'  Certain  phases,  I  will  not  say  of  pragmatism, 
but  of  the  opinions  and  doctrinal  affinities  of  pragmatists,  are 
greatly  illuminated  by  his  paper,  which  is,  moreover,  manifestly 
inspired  by  a  genuinely  philosophic  desire  to  cooperate  in  an  en- 
deavor to  promote  a  common  understanding.  Nevertheless — such 
are  the  difficulties  of  philosophical  discussion! — even  this  most 
generous  and  fair-minded  of  critics  has  apparently  altogether  over- 
looked the  principal  point  of  my  argument;  and  the  reasonings 
which  he  presents  appear  to  me  to  be  not  only  inconclusive,  but 
almost  wholly  irrelevant  to  the  particular  issue  upon  which  I  had 
hoped  to  focus  attention.  Yet  they  are  apparently  believed  by 
their  author  to  controvert  the  conclusions  I  defended ;  and  it  seems 
needful,  therefore,  to  examine  carefully  the  chief  considerations 
which  Professor  Bode  contributes  to  the  discussion. 

1.  A  great  part  of  his  reply  is  devoted  to  an  explanation  of  what 
the  pragmatist  means  by  "consciousness."  He  is  not  disposed 
wholly  to  reject  this  term;  he  too  is  ready  to  formulate,  in  his 
own  way,  a  "differentia  of  the  psychic"  and  a  criterion  "which 
makes  it  possible  to  draw  a  sharp  line  between  conscious  and  me- 
chanical behavior."  This,  of  course,  is  of  much  interest  in  itself; 
but  it  has  no  pertinency  to  the  reasons  for  affirming  the  existence 
of  "psychical"  entities  which  were  presented  in  my  paper.  To 
say  that  for  the  instrumentalist  "consciousness  is  identifiable  with" 
such  and  such  a  ' '  type  of  behavior, ' '  is  equivalent  to  the  two  propo- 
sitions (1)  that  by  the  word  "consciousness"  the  instrumentalist 
means  the  defined  type  of  behavior;  (2)  that  such  a  type  of  be- 
havior is  empirically  discoverable.  The  first,  being  a  verbal  propo- 
sition, requires  no  proof.  The  second  is  a  proposition  of  fact  and 
therefore  subject  to  verification.  But  its  truth  might  be  conceded 
without  the  least  logical  detriment  to  the  considerations  which  I 
had  advanced.  For  I  have  not  questioned  the  pragmatist 's  right 
to  define  the  word  "consciousness"  as  he  likes;  I  have  not  denied 
that  the  "peculiar  type  of  behavior"  to  which  Professor  Bode 
prefers  to  apply  that  name  is  a  fact  of  experience ;  and  I  have  not 

»  VoL  XVIII,  1921,  pp.  10-17. 


PRAGMATISM  AND  THE  NEW  MATERIALISM          9 

maintained  that  this  type  of  behavior  affords  evidence  that  "mental 
entities,"  in  my  sense  of  the  term,  exist.  What  I  have  maintained 
is  that  there  is  also  found  in  human  experience  a  phenomenon  dif- 
fering in  certain  important  respects  from  that  which  Professor 
Bode  describes;  and  that  this  does  afford  evidence  of  the  existence 
of  mental  entities.  This  other  sort  of  experience,  exemplified  in 
planning  and  all  forms  of  practical  reflection,  is  what  I  had  sup- 
posed the  pragmatist  to  mean  by  "intelligence";  but  I  am  less 
interested  in  ascertaining  the  pragmatic  name  for  the  thing  than  in 
pointing  out  that  the  thing  is  a  fact.  Throughout  most  of  his  paper, 
then,  Professor  Bode,  instead  of  looking  at  the  evidence  offered 
for  this  conclusion,  which  he  ostensibly  rejects,  appears  to  fix  his 
gaze  upon  another  object  altogether.  Let  me  show  this  in  detail 
by  outlining  more  specifically  the  pragmatic  account  of  "conscious- 
ness," as  set  forth  by  him.  The  pragmatist  observes  that  some 
stimuli  are  of  a  "peculiar  kind,"  i.e.,  have  specific  characteristics 
which  others  lack.  For  example,  a  noise  in  some  cases  has,  in  ad- 
dition to  the  "various  properties  or  qualities  that  are  appropriate 
subject-matter  for  the  physicist,  a  further  trait  or  quality"  of 
which  the  physicist  takes  no  cognizance.  This  further  trait  is,  it 
appears,  an  "elusive"  one,  difficult  to  express  in  words;  but  its 
nature  is  indicated  by  such  expressions  as  "an  indescribable  'what- 
is-it'  quality,"  an  "inherent  incompleteness."  When  a  noise  pos- 
sesses, besides  its  mere  noisiness,  this  special  and  unique  quality, 
it  "causes  the  individual  concerned  to  cock  his  ear,  to  turn  his  eyes, 
perhaps  to  step  to  the  window  in  order  to  ascertain  the  meaning 
of  the  noise."  Stimuli  (a  term  which  is  for  Bode  apparently 
synonymous  with  complexes  of  sensible  qualities)  are,  then,  said 
to  be  "conscious"  if  they  have  this  peculiarity;  and  "conscious- 
ness" is  a  name  for  the  "function  of  a  quality  in  giving  direction 
to  behavior."  The  conscious  stimulus,  in  other  words,  is  differ- 
entiated by  its  tendency  "to  set  on  foot  activities  which  are  di- 
rected towards  getting  a  better  stimulus."  The  word  "directed" 
here,  however,  must  not  be  understood  to  imply  any  representation 
of  the  better  stimulus  as  future ;  for  a  reaction  possesses  the  ' '  psychi- 
cal ' '  character  ' '  irrespective  of  any  explicit  reference  to  the  future. ' ' 
There  need  be  no  actual  anticipation,  of  the  "conceptual"  sort. 
Any  case  of  organic  response  which  exhibits  the  phenomenon  of 
trial-and-error  would  apparently  exemplify  "conscious"  behavior, 
in  the  pragmatist 's  sense;  in  fact  I  can  not  see  that  there  is  any 
kind  of  actual  response  which  would  not  correspond  to  the  defini- 
tion. 

There  are — it  may  be  observed  incidentally — some  inconveni- 


10  THE  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY 

ences  in  using  the  words  "psychical,"  "mental,"  etc.,  in  this 
manner.  One  of  them  is  that  "psychical"  apparently  does  not  ex- 
clude "physical."  If  I  understand  Bode's  language,  a  real  physi- 
cal object  would  also  be  a  "psychical  existence"  whenever  it  "set 
on  foot  activities  directed  towards  getting  a  better  stimulus."  It 
is  also  a  somewhat  confusing  feature  of  this  usage  that  the  adjec- 
tives "conscious,"  "psychical,"  etc.,  seem  applicable  both  to 
stimuli  and  to  the  bodily  behavior  which  the  stimuli  evoke,  though 
it  is  difficult  to  see  how  they  can  be  attached  to  both  substantives 
univocally. 

This,  however,  is  by  the  way.  What  I  wish  to  point  out  is  that 
my  argument  rested  entirely  upon  an  analysis  of  the  particular 
kind  of  reaction  in  which  there  is  an  "explicit  reference  to  the 
future" — in  which  actual  foresight  is  an  essential  feature  of  the 
experience.  By  transferring  the  adjective  "psychical"  to  a  kind 
of  reaction  defined  as  lacking  this  feature,  Professor  Bode  does 
not  answer  that  argument;  he  simply  ignores  it.  Is  it  a  fact  that 
explicit  reference  to  the  future  sometimes  occurs,  that  when  we 
form  a  plan  of  action  unrealized  possibilities  are  present  as  such 
to  our  thought  ?  Or  again,  is  it  a  fact  that  when  we  think  of  such 
unrealized  concrete  possibilities  we  have  present  in  thought  objects 
which  can  not  be  regarded  as  parts  of  the  present  content  of  the 
material  world?  Only  by  answering  the  first  of  these  questions  in 
the  negative,  or,  if  that  were  answered  affirmatively,  then  by  an- 
swering the  second  in  the  negative,  could  Bode  join  issue  with  the 
reasoning  actually  contained  in  the  papers  upon  which  he  com- 
ments. A  radical  behaviorist,  I  suppose,  would  answer  one  or  the 
other  of  these  questions  with  an  unequivocal  negative.  But  it  is 
not  clear  from  Professor  Bode's  article  that  he  shares  the  behavior- 
ist's  fine  a  priori  contempt  for  the  facts  of  experience. 

2.  There  is,  however,  a  further  aspect  of  the  pragmatist's  con- 
ception of  "conscious  behavior"  which  is  not  fully  brought  out  in 
the  summary  above  given;  and  this  we  must  now  examine,  since 
it  is  this  aspect  chiefly  which  makes  it  clear  "why  instrumental  ism 
is  so  reluctant  to  bring  in  mental  states  or  psychic  existences." 
(The  latter  expression  is  presumably  here  used  in  the  sense  defined 
in  my  previous  papers;  for  Professor  Bode  has  just  told  us  that 
in  another  sense,  pragmatism  itself  recognizes  psychic  existences.) 

The  argument,  if  I  have  understood  it,  rests  upon  a  distinctive 
thesis  about  the  attributes  of  "objects."  The  pragmatist,  it  would 
seem,  holds  that  what  are  usually  called  the  effects  of  a  stimulus 
upon  an  organism  should  properly  be  called  "parts"  of  the  stimu- 
lus, or  attributes  of  the  object  (for  Bode  apparently  uses  the  two 


PRAGMATISM  AND  THE  NEW  MATERIALISM         11 

terms  interchangeably).    In  the  case  of  a  noise  which  causes  a  dog 
to  cock  his  ear,  the  attribute  of  causing-ear-cocking,  "by  which  the 
present  stimulus  makes  provision  for  its  own  successor,"  is  des- 
ignated in  pragmatist  terminology  the  "incompleteness"   of  the 
present  stimulus ;  and  this  ' '  incompleteness  is  intrinsic  to  the  stimu- 
lus, or  inherent  in  it";  in  other  words,  it  is  "as  much  a  part  of 
the  noise  as  any  of  its  other  traits."    Since  the  behavior  resulting, 
or  capable  of  resulting,  from  a  given  stimulus  is  thus  read  back 
into  the  stimulus  itself,  and  since  the  stimulus  in  turn  is  identified 
with  physical  objects  (and,  in  the  case  of  perception,  apparently 
with  the  physical  object  perceived),  there  results  for  the  pragmatist 
a  radical  revision  of  the  conception  of  physical  objects.     "Tradi- 
tional theory"  has  been  wont  to  regard  such  an  object  as  "charac- 
terized by  stark  rigidity  and  close-clipped  edges";  to  the  pragmat- 
ist, on  the  contrary,  it  seems  to  be  a  soft  and  plastic  entity  with 
boundaries  so  wide  that  almost  anything  might  be  found  within 
them.     The  notion  of  the  "inherent  properties  of  an  object"  is 
thus  so  enlarged  as  to  include  either   (Bode  does  not  seem  to  me 
to  be  clear  here)  all  organic  responses  which  the  object's  presence 
ever  evokes,  or,  at  any  rate,  an  inherent  tendency  to  evoke  what- 
ever responses  in  fact  occur  when  it  is  present.     Physical  objects 
are  consequently  things  which  can  control  behavior  directly,  by- 
virtue  of  their  own  nature  and  attributes ;  and  it  therefore  becomes-* 
unnecessary  to  introduce  mental  entities  in  the  explanation  of  be- 
havior, .in  man  or  other  animals.    ' '  The  emphasis  shifts  inevitably 
from  mental  states  in  the  traditional  sense  to  this  peculiar  type  of 
control  as  exercised  by  objects."4    It  is  precisely  because  pragmat- 
ism has  become  aware  of  "this  distinctive  character  of  the  stimu- 
lus" that  it  "can  not  afford  to  give  countenance  to  entities  or  ex- 
istences the  chief  purpose  of  which, "  as  it  seems  to  Professor  Bode, 
is  to  obscure  this  character — to  "translate  it  into  mechanical  equiv- 
alents. ' ' 

To  judge  of  the  pertinency  of  this  reasoning  it  is  needful  to  re- 
call once  more — however  wearisome  the  repetition — the  precise  argu- 
ment against  which  it  is  supposed  to  be  directed.  That  argument, 
it  will  be  remembered,  (a)  dealt  exclusively  with  the  evidence  for 
the  existence  of  non-physical  entities  to  be  found  in  a  particular 
phase  of  human  experience,  viz.,  in  intelligent  planning,  involving 
an  explicit  representation  of  things  past  and  future;  (&)  used  the 
expressions  "psychical"  or  "non-physical  entity"  in  a  specific  and 
clearly  defined  sense,  viz.,  as  meaning  "an  entity  not  assignable  to 
real  space  and  to  the  complex  of  matter  and  forces  recognized  by 

*  Op.  tit.,  p.  15;  italics  in  original. 


12        THE  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY 

the  physical  sciences,  at  the  moment  at  which  the  entity  is  actually 
present  in  experience."  The  reasoning  offered  as  the  principal 
reply  to  this  argument  (a)  still  wholly  ignores  the  specific  type  of 
experience  to  which  the  argument  related.  It  offers,  not  an  analy- 
sis of  anticipation  and  memory,  but  an  analysis  of  sensory  stimula- 
tion. 1  ask  the  pragmatist  about  "intelligence,"  and  am  given  a 
description  of  responses  for  which  no  intelligence  is  requisite.  I 
ask  what  precisely  it  is  that  happens  when  an  architect  plans  a 
building,  or  when  an  engineer  endeavors  to  analyze  the  causes  of 
the  collapse  of  the  St.  Lawrence  bridge  several  years  ago;  Pro- 
fessor Bode  replies  by  telling  me  what  it  is  that  happens  when  a 
dog  cocks  his  ear.  As  described,  moreover,  "conscious  behavior" 
is  not  distinguishable  from  the  kind  of  phenomenon  which  occurs 
when  a  phototropic  plant  is  touched  by  a  ray  of  light.  In  the  case 
of  the  plant  also  the  initial  stimulus  "makes  provision  for  its  own 
successor"  and  "sets  on  foot  activities  directed  towards  getting  a 
better  stimulus."  (6)  With  respect  to  the  question,  irrelevant  to 
my  argument,  with  which  Bode's  reply  is  actually  concerned,  his 
conclusion  is  reached  by  a  series  of  partly  explicit  and  partly 
tacit  alterations  in  the  meanings  of  terms.  He  first  includes  the 
adaptive  motor-responses  to  a  sensation  among  the  "traits"  of  the 
sense-datum  itself;  he  next  tacitly  identifies  the  sense-datum  ("the 
noise  as  heard")  with  the  "stimulus"  (which  in  the  ordinary  u-<- 
of  terms  means,  in  the  case  of  audition,  the  air  wave  set  up  by 
the  vibration  of  an  elastic  body)  ;  he  then  identifies  the  stimulus 
with  the  "object" — presumably  the  object  from  which  it  proceeds, 
e.g.,  an  automobile-horn.  By  this  process  of  freely  substituting  one 
meaning  for  another,  it  is  assuredly  not  difficult  to  prove  that  tho 
dog's  cocking  his  ear  is  merely  an  instance  of  "the  control  of  be- 
havior by  objects."  But  the  entire  argument  is  of  an  essentially 
verbal  character;  and  the  first  two  steps  in  it — the  identification 
of  responses  with  sense-data,  and  of  sense-data  with  external 
stimuli — beg  the  only  question  to  which  the  argument  can  be  said 
to  be  directed.  For  that  question  is  whether  sensory  content  is 
totally  identical  with  either  the  stimulus  or  the  physical  state  of 
the  sensory  nerves;  and  whether  the  stimulation  passes  over  into 
a  motor  response  without  the  generation  or  interposition,  any- 
where in  the  process,  of  any  factor  which  is  not  "physical"  in  the 
ordinary  sense,  previously  defined.  That  is  a  question  of  fact  which 
is  hardly  to  be  settled  by  the  short  and  easy  method  of  defining 
physical  objects  ab  initio  as  havinpr  an  inherent  virtus  excitatn'a 
sufficient  of  itself  to  account  for  behavior. 

What  might  at  first  be  taken  for  a  further  distinct  argument 


PRAGMATISM  AND  THE  NEW  MATERIALISM         13 

against  psychophysical  dualism  and  interactionism  is  suggested  by 
Professor  Bode 's  repeated  remark  that  those  doctrines  imply  a 
"mechanistic"  conception  of  behavior.  "Unless  we  abandon  the 
category  of  interactionism  we  are  back  on  the  level  of  mechanistic 
naturalism,  from  which  the  position  of  instrumentalism  is  intended 
to  provide  a  means  of  escape."  But  it  is  obvious  that  the  adjec- 
tive must  here  be  used  in  some  peculiar  sense;  for  nothing  is  more 
alien  to  "mechanistic  naturalism,"  as  that  designation  is  usually 
understood,  than  the  doctrine  that  non-physical  entities  or  proc- 
esses can  affect  the  movements  of  bodies.  When,  then,  we  seek  to 
determine  precisely  what  Bode  means  by  "mechanistic,"  we  find 
that  the  word  apparently  denotes  any  view  which  regards  as  in- 
correct or  insufficient  the  account  of  the  ' '  distinctive  nature  of  con- 
scious behavior"  given  by  the  pragmatist.  "Mechanical  behavior," 
in  short,  is  expressly  antithetic  to  "conscious  behavior,"  in  the 
pragmatist 's  sense;  and  "conscious  behavior"  in  his  sense  means, 
as  we  have  seen,  behavior  controlled  by  physical  objects  directly, 
by  virtue  of  their  "inherent  incompleteness" — this  last  expression, 
in  turn,  meaning  a  capacity  to  initiate  in  an  organism  (without  the 
intervention  of  any  other  factors)  a  series  of  adaptive  responses. 
In  brief,  the  charge  that  psychological  interactionism  is  "mechan- 
istic" means,  when  translated,  that  that  doctrine  affirms  the  pres- 
ence and  efficacy  of  factors  other  than  physical  objects  in  at  least 
some  modes  of  human  behavior.  The  charge,  in  short,  is  that 
interactionism  is — interactionism.  There  is  here,  therefore,  no  ar- 
gument which  seems  to  demand  separate  discussion. 

3.  After  having,  through  nearly  all  of  his  article,  vigorously 
assailed  the  belief  in  mental  or  psychical  entities  (in  my  sense  of 
the  terms),  Professor  Bode  in  his  penultimate  paragraph  suddenly 
and  surprisingly  utters  a  profession  of  faith  in  the  creed  which  he 
had  seemed  to  be  attacking.  "We  need  not,"  he  writes,  "take 
serious  exception  to  Love  joy's  contention  that  concepts  are  'mental 
entities,'  in  the  sense  that  they  may  be  'actually  given  .  .  .  but 
can  not  be  regarded  as  forming  a  part,  at  the  same  moment,  of  the 
complex  of  masses  and  forces,  in  a  single  public  space,  which  con- 
stitutes the  world  of  physical  science.'  That  concepts  exist  in 
some  form  and  that  there  is  a  discernible  difference  between  them 
and  physical  objects  is  an  indubitable  fact."  These  "concepts," 
moreover,  are  functional.  "They  function  in  much  the  same  way 
as  physical  objects;"  they  "control  behavior."  Here,  it  will  be 
observed,  it  is  explicitly  in  the  sense  which  I  had  given  to  "mental" 
that  Professor  Bode  grants  the  reality  of  mental  entities.  He  adds, 
it  is  true,  that  "the  important  issue  is  not  whether  concepts  exist, 


14  THE  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY 

but  whether  the  classification  of  them  as  'mental'  is  to  be  made  to 
accord  with  the  foregoing  (i.e.,  the  pragmatic)  theory  of  conscious 
behavior."  This  might  be  taken  to  mean  that,  after  all,  he  regards 
concepts  as  "mental"  solely  in  the  pragmatic  sense,  not  in  the 
sense  given  in  the  definition  which  he  quotes  from  my  paper.  But 
to  construe  his  meaning  thus  would  be  to  imply  that  he  denies  in 
one  sentence  what  he  had  affirmed  two  sentences  before;  and  no 
such  interpretation,  happily,  is  necessary.  For  a  "  concept "- 
e.g.,  a  representation  of  a  building  yet  to  be  erected — may  be 
"mental"  both  in  the  sense  expressed  by  my  definition  and  in  a 
sense  which  includes  at  least  the  distinctive  positive  differentia 
of  the  "psychical"  in  the  pragmatic  definition.  A  non-physical 
factor  in  experience  may — and  if  it  be  efficacious,  must — function 
like  any  other  stimulus.  The  idea  of  the  house  to  be  built  will 
necessarily  have  what  Bode  calls  an  "unfinished  quality;"  it  too 
will  be  "directed  towards  the  end  of  completing  the  present  incom- 
pleteness." But  its  possession  of  this  character  does  not  alter  the 
fact  that,  unlike  other  possible  varieties  of  "psychical"  stimuli — in 
the  pragmatic  meaning  of  the  term — it  consists  in  a  representation 
of  a  future  object,  and  is  therefore  "psychical"  in  another  sense, 
a  sense  which  excludes  it  from  the  class  of  physical  things,  i.e.,  of 
things  belonging  to  the  objective  spatial  system. 

Professor  Bode,  then,  though  he  has  elsewhere  represented  the 
psychical  as  merely  a  special  variety  of  the  physical,  now  seems  to 
tell  us  plainly  (a)  that  there  are  two  distinct  classes  of  factors  in 
our  experience,  "physical  objects"  and  "mental  entities;"  (&) 
that  both  are  efficacious  in  the  causation  of  physical  changes. 
These  two  propositions  taken  together  seem  to  constitute  the  plain- 
est possible  affirmation  of  psychophysical  dualism  and  interaction- 
ism — as,  I  take  it,  those  terms  are  commonly  understood.  Yet  the 
same  passage  concludes:  "There  is  no  ground  for  Lovejoy's  conten- 
tion that,  if  concepts  are  admitted  to  their  legitimate  place,  it  fol- 
lows that,  rightly  constructed  and  consistently  thought  through,  prag- 
matism means  interactionism. "  Here  I  must  confess  myself  baffled. 
How  this  conclusion  is  to  be  reconciled  with  the  admissions  which 
immediately  precede  it,  I  am  unable  to  conjecture.  I  therefore 
can  not  feel  that  Professor  Bode  has  succeeded  in  making  his  posi- 
tion, or  that  of  pragmatists  in  general,  unmistakably  clear.  After 
careful  study  of  his  paper,  I  remain  in  some  doubt  whether  he  holds 
that  pragmatism  implies  materialism  or  not. 

It  still  seems  to  me  desirable,  however,  that  the  matter  should 
be  made  clear,  and  that  pragmatists  (not  to  speak  of  others)  should 
actually  give  some  consideration  to  the  reasons  offered  in  support 


A  PARTIAL  ANALYSIS  OF  FAITH  15 

of  the  view  that  the  pragmatic  doctrine  of  the  efficacy  of  intelli- 
gence properly  implies  psychophysical  dualism  and  interactionism. 
And  in  the  hope  that  Professor  Bode  himself,  or  others  of  the  sam« 
way  of  thinking,  may  again  deal  with  the  subject,  I  venture,  by 
way  of  conclusion  and  resume,  to  set  down  a  few  questions  to 
which  I  think  it  would  be  illuminating  to  have  clear  answers.  (1) 
Does  the  pragmatist  hold  that  only  physical  things  exist,  i.e.,  that 
they  alone  are  disclosed  by,  or  present  as  factors  in,  experience 
("physical"  meaning  "occupying  a  position  in  objective  space 
and  existing  as  a  part  of  the  sum  of  masses  and  forces  dealt  with 
by  physical  science")  ?  (2)  Is  it  not  a  fact  that  in  the  formation 
of  intelligent  plans  of  action  there  are  involved  both  "imaginative 
recovery  of  the  bygone"  and  imaginative  anticipation  of  objects 
and  situations  not  yet  physically  realized?  (3)  If  so,  can  every 
bit  of  the  content  presented  in  the  two  types  of  experience  just 
mentioned  be  regarded  as  forming  a  real  part  of  the  physical  world, 
as  constituted  at  the  moment  of  such  experience?  (4)  If  so,  where 
in  that  world,  and  in  what  form  or  manner,  does  the  "bygone" 
that  is  "imaginatively  recovered,"  or  the  future  that  is  not  yet 
realized,  exist?  (5)  If  it  does  exist  physically  at  the  moment  of 
the  experience  in  question,  precisely  what  is  meant  by  calling  it 
"bygone"  or  "future"?  To  the  last  four  of  these  questions  I  can 
not  but  think  that  all  partisans  of  the  new  materialism  might  profit- 
ably address  themselves. 

ARTHUR  0.  LOVE  JOY. 
JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY. 


A  PARTIAL  ANALYSIS  OF  FAITH 

ELIEVING  with  Eucken,  James,  Bergson,  and  other  philoso- 
phers  of  like  mind,  that  faith  plays  a  very  vital  part  in  the  lives 
of  us  all,  it  has  nevertheless  been  a  mystery  above  other  mysteries 
to  me  when  I  attempted  seriously  to  describe  it,  analyze  it,  and 
classify  it.  A  multiplicity  of  questions  have  arisen,  some  of  which 
have  become  so  defined  that  an  answer  seems  at  least  worth  while 
seeking.  Some  of  them  are :  What  is  the  function  of  faith,  what  does 
it  contribute  to  the  happiness  or  the  achievements  of  mankind? 
What  is  the  attitude  of  mind,  what  the  emotions,  what  the  nature 
of  the  contents  which  go  to  make  up  the  faith  states?  Is  it  some- 
thing that  grows  within  us  by  exercise  and  cultivation  as  the  per- 
ceiving and  reasoning  processes  do  ?  Does  it  correspond  to  something 
outside  of  us,  or  is  it  entirely  subjective,  something  within  us  ? 

A  first  difficulty  with  the  problem  lies  in  the  fact  that  few  of  us 


16         THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ever  attain,  or  but  seldom  attain,  to  the  pure  faith  states,  and  the 
element  of  faith  in  our  everyday  life  is  so  intermingled  with  other 
elements  in  the  stream  of  consciousness,  that  it  is  difficult  to  isolate 
it  for  purposes  of  introspection.  However  the  present  writer  through 
stress  of  much  illness  and  suffering  has  come  to  a  certain  practise  of 
faith  and  thereby  to  a  certain  understanding  of  it  as  practised  by 
others,  which  yields  a  degree  of  actual  comfort  and  logical  satisfac- 
tion. 

We  all  know  what  faith  means,  an  acceptance  of  that  which  has 
never  been  proven  and  may  be  impossible  of  proving.  Its  first  and 
most  fundamental  characteristic  seems  to  be  the  attitude  which  con- 
sciousness assumes  toward  any  matter.  This  attitude,  so  far  as  the 
present  introspectionist  is  concerned,  refuses  to  be  subsumed  under 
any  of  the  classes  of  attention  as  described  in  the  present  day 
psychologies,  and  seems  so  radically  different  that  to  posit  a  class  of 
attitudes  entirely  opposite  to  those  of  attention  offers  the  best  chances 
for  clear  analysis,  at  least  for  the  present.  Now  ordinarily,  we  meet 
the  common  situations  of  life  in  an  attitude  of  attention,  with  the 
responses  acquired  by  imitation,  habit,  or  reasoning.  We  depend 
on  ourselves,  on  our  past  experiences  as  known  to  consciousness  in 
remembering,  for  these  responses  and  receive  stimuli  and  carry  out 
reactions,  with  fluctuations  of  attention  as  to  kind  and  degree.  Con- 
sciousness, or  surface  consciousness,  goes  on  in  an  uninterrupted 
flow.  But  a  new  situation  arises  or  an  old  one  becomes  intolerable 
with  which  one  feels  unable  to  cope.  No  amount  of  thinking  carried 
on  with  the  utmost  concentration  of  attention  seems  to  avail.  A 
man  with  faith  habits  then  suspends  all  efforts  and  waits  for  an 
inspiration  or  guiding  thought  to  come;  if  from  within,  we  call  it 
auto-suggestion  or  intuition ;  if  from  another,  it  is  called,  suggestion ; 
if  it  appears  to  come  from  a  divine  source,  it  is  prayer  or  an  answer 
to  prayer. 

Now  the  general  nature  of  what  the  individual  does  is  the  same 
in  all  cases.  He  drops  the  attitude  of  attention,  stops  the  thinking 
going  on  under  the  dominance  of  a  controlling  idea  with  carefully 
selected  associations.  He  assumes  a  waiting  or  expectant  attitude  in 
throwing  open  his  mind  as  it  were  in  the  belief  that  a  suitable  idea 
or  thought  will  appear  to  fill  the  existing  vacancy.  The  common 
expressions  such  as  "I  was  at  my  wits'  end  when  all  at  once  I  had  a 
lucky  thought,"  or,  "I  was  in  despair  when  suddenly  an  inspira- 
tion came,"  illustrate  one  type  of  response  of  the  first  sort,  namely, 
the  appeal,  perhaps  unconscious,  to  something  within  one,  other  than 
the  surface  stream  of  thought,  call  it  the  subconscious,  or  what  you 
will.  The  second  sort  of  response,  or  suggestion,  is  found  when  peo- 


A  PARTIAL  ANALYSIS  OF  FAITH  17 

pie  go  to  the  confessional,  to  clairvoyants,  or  resort  to  some  stereo- 
typed form  of  response  such  as  fortune  telling  by  cards,  opening  a 
book  at  random  and  being  guided  by  the  first  words  read.  Young 
children  appeal  to  parents  or  other  adults  in  this  way  and  if  a  proper 
spirit  is  cultivated  in  the  family  the  different  members  appeal  to 
one  another  in  this  fashion  and  exemplify  as  nothing  else  does  the 
raison  d'etre  of  family  life.  The  third  response,  appeal  to  a  Divine 
Power,  is  of  course  prayer,  epitomized  in  the  Gethsemane  utterance, 
"Not  my  will,  but  Thine  be  done."  It  betokens  the  inhibition  of 
the  dominant  thought  in  the  fullest  degree,  and  the  most  complete 
submission  to  whatever  may  come  from  the  outside,  or  from  within, 
as  one  accepts  the  transcendent  or  the  immanent  idea  of  God. 

The  term  expectancy  is  by  no  means  new  in  philosophical  writ- 
ings. Eibot  has  used  it  in  his  Evolution  of  General  Ideas,  saying 
that  to  simple  association  expectancy  must  be  added  before  reason- 
ing takes  place.1  Consciousness  must  assume  the  expectant  attitude 
in  order  for  the  ideas  to  take  on  the  correct  relationship  which  is 
necessary  in  the  processes  called  reasoning.  James  uses  the  word 
repeatedly  in  his  essay,  "The  Sentiment  of  Rationality,"  without 
giving  it  any  very  specific  meaning  other  than  a  general  state  of  mind 
when  uncertainty  in  regard  to  future  events  beyond  our  control  is 
present,  as  for  example  in  the  following.  ' '  The  permanent  presence 
of  the  sense  of  futurity  in  the  mind  has  been  strangely  ignored  by 
most  writers,  but  the  fact  is  that  our  consciousness  at  a  given  moment 
is  never  free  from  the  ingredient  of  expectancy. "  2  Or  again :  ' '  An 
ultimate  datum,  even  though  it  be  logically  unrationalized,  will,  if 
its  quality  is  such  as  to  define  expectancy,  be  peacefully  accepted  by 
the  mind."  3  Whether  one  is  justified  in  using  the  word  to  describe 
or  name  a  fundamental  attitude  of  the  mind  different  from  attention 
is  another  matter.  If  such  a  class  exists,  I  know  of  no  other  word  so 
appropriate  unless  it  be  that  of  waiting,  and  while  very  appropriate 
for  some  of  this  class,  yet  it  carries  with  it  too  much  the  idea  of 
passivity,  while  expectancy  denotes  an  eager  looking  forward,  a 
quality  which  caused  the  poet  to  write  of  faith  as  a  "living  flame." 
On  the  other  hand  "waiting  stillness"  is  very  much  used  by  the 
mystics  to  describe  the  quiet  confident  repose  of  the  soul  in  deepest 
meditation.  The  expression  "waiting  on  the  Lord"  is  especially 
frequent  in  the  writings  of  the  Hebrew  psalmists:  "I  waited  for  the 
Lord,  He  inclined  unto  me, "  "  My  soul  doth  wait  upon  the  Lord. ' ' 

When  we  come  to  consider  the  content  of  faith  we  can  only  say 

1  Ribot,  Evolution  of  General  Ideas,  p.  25. 

2  James,  Essays  in  Popular  Philosophy,  p.  77. 

3  Ibid.,  p.  79. 


18  THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

that  any  thing  whose  outcome  lies  in  the  future  may  constitute  an 
object  of  faith,  but  the  universal  and  persistent  content  of  faith  has 
to  do  with  the  welfare  of  the  individual  soul,  now  and  hereafter, 
with  salvation  and  immortality;  with  the  existence  and  purposes  of 
God,  the  Universal  Soul,  as  it  were;  with  the  relationships  of  one 
soul  to  another  and  to  God ;  in  short,  those  things  regarding  which 
our  logical  concepts  and  laws  seem  inadequate  and  whose  future  we 
can  not  forecast  with  any  demonstrable  certainty.  With  many  peo- 
ple the  welfare  of  the  body  is  also  in  a  peculiar  manner  the  substance 
of  faith  and  all  sorts  of  people  assert  the  efficacy  of  faith  in  the  cure 
of  physical  ills.  That  faith  in  the  cure  of  physical  ills  and  in  the 
cure  of  sin  is  in  its  essential  features  the  same  thing  from  a  psychol- 
ogical standpoint,  the  writer  has  tried  to  show  in  a  former  article.4 
This  view  receives  strong  confirmation  in  an  essay  by  a  Catholic 
Father  of  Oxford  who  finds  that  the  directions  given  by  St.  Ignatius 
several  centuries  ago  for  practising  spiritual  exercises  are  the  same, 
mutatis  mutandis,  as  those  given  by  the  modern  mental  healer  for 
physical  cure.  Taking  psychoanalysis  as  an  example  of  mental 
psychotherapeutics  which  has  the  highest  claim  to  being  scientific 
he  says:  "Psychoanalysis  is  based  on  the  principle  that  there  is  a 
subconscious  self  which  can  do  things  which  we  can  not  do  volun- 
tarily and  seeks  by  means  of  suggestion  to  utilise  the  subconscious 
machinery.  Substitute  for  the  subconscious  self,  God,  and  you  have 
the  fundamental  principle  of  the  Spiritual  Exercises."  5 

But  these  subjects  mentioned  above  have  from  time  immemorial 
formed  the  subject  matter  for  intellectual  speculation  and  scientific 
experimentation,  and  reams  upon  reams  have  been  written  offering 
proofs  concerning  truths  accepted  at  that  time,  none  of  which  have 
been  able  to  stand  the  test  of  newer  facts  and  experiences.  How  is 
it  then  that  faith  can  handle  these  same  matters  and  make  them  active 
forces  in  the  lives  of  individuals?  In  his  Essay,  "The  Will  to  Be- 
lieve," James  makes  this  statement:  "In  truths  dependent  on  our 
personal  actions,  then,  faith  based  on  desire  is  certainly  a  lawful 
and  possibly  an  indispensable  thing."  e  I  believe  that  faith  is  always 
based  on  desire,  but  for  the  matter  of  that  so  is  willing,  but  with  a 
difference.  Desire  is  a  state  of  consciousness  which  terminates  in 
judgments,  decisions,  and  acts,  provided  a  will  or  action  complex  can 
be  found  to  complete  the  desire  satisfactorily  to  consciousness  as  a 
whole.  If  none  such  presents  itself  in  the  stream  of  consciousness, 

*"  A  Glimpse  into  Mysticism  and  the  Faith  State."  This  JOURNAL,  Vol. 
XVII,  pp.  708-715,  Dec.  16,  1920. 

•  Walker, ' '  The  Spiritual  Exercises  of  St.  Ignatius, ' '  Hib.  Jour.,  April,  1921. 

•  P.  25. 


A  PARTIAL  ANALYSIS  OF  FAITH  19 

then  the  desire  falls  below  the  threshold  and  exists  as  unexpressed 
desire — vague  and  undetermined  as  to  outcome  and  in  many  cases 
the  cause  of  a  disturbed  emotional  state.  If  thwarted  or  incomplete 
desires  in  regard  to  a  certain  matter  are  many,  that  is,  if  conscious- 
ness continues  to  find  no  satisfactory  completion  of  the  desires,  a 
state  of  inadequacy  appears,  consciousness  inhibits  itself,  throws 
wide  the  gates  which  guard  the  threshold  so  carefully  in  the  process 
of  remembering  in  a  state  of  attention,  and  assumes  a  state  of  expec- 
tancy. Into  the  void  thus  formed,  springs  the  desire  with  all  the 
weight  of  accumulation  with  the  same  action  complex  which  before 
could  not  force  its  way  into  the  stream  of  thought  or  at  least  not 
with  enough  strength  to  bring  a  decision.  The  impulses  and  desires, 
weak  as  regards  the  dominant  lines  of  thought  and  action,  prevail 
when  they  have  brought  about  a  state  of  uneasiness  which  leads  to 
the  inhibiting  of  these  dominant  lines. 

Perhaps  we  find  the  best  example  of  this  in  religious  conversion. 
Underneath  the  many  failures  were  the  impulses,  the  strivings, 
the  desire  to  do  better  which  ultimately  brought  about  a  state  of 
repentance,  and  prevailing  over  the  old  dominating  line  of  action, 
culminated  in  a  new  state  of  consciousness  which  is  called  the  new 
birth  in  Christian  teaching.  It  is  the  bringing  of  consciousness  to 
higher  levels  in  the  terminology  of  Eucken,  which  reorganization 
he  ascribes  to  the  mercy  of  God,  to  free  grace.  Personally,  I  too 
believe  that  God  reenforces  these  designs;  that  He  is  an  active  force 
in  us,  sublimating  the  "natural  desires"  and  motivating  our  weaker 
but  higher  ideals  and  aspirations.  Of  this,  of  course  I  offer  no 
logical  proof,  but  only  add  my  testimony  to  that  of  others  who 
live  and  act  by  the  same  faith. 

Prayer  is  the  generally  accepted  mental  process  of  faith  and 
is  undeniably  based  on  desire.  In  the  words  of  the  familiar  hymn, 
"Prayer  is  the  soul's  sincere  desire,  unuttered  or  expressed." 
St.  Augustine's  admonition,  "for  to  journey  thither  [towards  God], 
nay  even  to  arrive  there  is  nothing  else  but  the  will  to  go,"  forms 
the  nucleus  of  an  interesting  story  of  modern  life,  giving  a  psy- 
chologically true  account  of  the  transition  of  a  weary  restless  soul 
to  a  joyous  peacefulness  though  the  strength  of  her  desire.7  Again 
the  Hebrew  psalmist  has  expressed  the  thought  so  perfectly.  ' '  Rest 
in  the  Lord,  wait  patiently  for  him;  Delight  thyself  also  in  the 
Lord  and  he  shall  give  thee  thy  heart's  desire." 

Faith  healing  of  the  body  follows  in  the  main  the  same  proce- 
dure, as  said  before.  First,  all  mental  therapeutists  and  indeed 
all  practitioners  recognize  the  need  of  the  desire  for  health.  A  lady 

T  Montague,  "  The  Will  to  Go,"  Atlantic  Mo.,  May,  1921. 


20         THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

who  had  been  iimane  for  some  time  once  expressed  the  wish  to  a 
vi^it iii'j  triciid  that  she  might  recover  and  leave  the  hospital.  ThU 
waa  reported  to  the  head  physician,  who  replied  that  there  was 
then  a  chance  of  her  recovery,  and  she  did  recover.  The  Christian 
Scientists  teach  th«-ir  patients  to  desire  health,  tn  think  health,  and 
to  believe  health  is  coming.  It  is  difficult,  in  the  present  state  of 
knowledge  regarding  the  interaction  of  the  mind  and  the  body, 
to  say  why  this  is  necessary.  In  general  one  may  say  that  probably 
the  normal  functioning  of  the  body  depends  on  the  proper  distribu- 
tion of  nerve  energy  to  the  different  organs  and  parts  of  the  body. 
In  certain  cases,  especially  chronic  ones,  the  mind  seems  in  some 
way  to  have  played  a  part  in  the  altering  of  the  course  of  the  nerve 
currents  and  by  a  different  mode  of  thinking  can  help  to  restore 
normality.  Fear  has  an  inhibitory  and  generally  harmful  effect 
on  bodily  functions,  and  hope  and  confidence  have  a  helpful  one. 
Psychologists  by  method  of  psychical  analysis  believe  they  have 
discovered  that  certain  people  take  refuge  in  illness  to  escape  some 
situation  they  fear.  The  removal  of  the  fear  constitutes  the  main 
factor  in  the  cure,  and  physical  and  mental  energy  flow  again  in 
natural  channels.  All  suggestion,  from  auto-suggestion  to  hypno- 
tism, is  based  on  the  principle  of  the  inhibition  of  the  stream  of  con- 
sciousness and  on  the  attitude  of  readiness  to  receive  a  new  content. 
This  content  must,  as  we  have  said,  be  based  on  desire  and  as  most 
people  desire  health  very  ardently,  however  much  they  may  fear 
a  certain  situation  to  which  they  are  called  upon  to  react,  mental 
cures  are  very  often  easily  effected. 

Dr.  Prince  has  set  forth  this  theory  very  clearly  in  the  follow- 
ing paragraphs  as  regards  the  new  thought  processes  and  his  emo- 
tion is  equivalent  to  our  idea  of  desire.  "By  similar  procedures  in 
a  very  large  number  of  instances,  for  therapeutic  purposes,  7  have 
changed  the  setting,  the  viewpoint,  and  the  meaning  of  ideas  with- 
out any  realization  on  the  patients'  part  of  the  reason  for  the 
change.  This  is  the  goal  of  psychotherapy,  and  in  my  judgment 
the  one  fundamental  principle  common  to  all  technical  methods  of 
such  treatments,  different  as  these  methods  appear  to  be  when 
superficially  considered. 

"It  is  obvious  that  in  everyday  life  when  by  arguments,  per- 
suasion, suggestion,  punishment,  exhortation,  or  prayer  we  change 
the  viewpoint  of  a  person,  we  do  so  by  building  up  complexes  which 
shall  act  as  settings  and  give  new  meanings  to  his  ideas.  I  may 
add,  if  we  wish  to  sway  him,  to  carry  this  new  viewpoint  to  ful- 
fillment through  action  we  introduce  into  the  complex  an  emotion 
which  by  the  driving  force  of  its  impulses  shall  carry  the  ideas  to 
practical  fruition." 


A  PARTIAL  ANALYSIS  OF  FAITH  21 

Again  he  says :  ' '  With  excitation  of  emotion,  instincts  and  senti- 
ments which  have  opposing  conative  tendencies  are  inhibited,  re- 
pressed, or  dissociated  and  with  them  the  systems  with  which  they 
are  organized. ' ' 8  Here  again  we  read  desire,  which  I  believe  to 
be  the  basis  of  most  if  not  all  emotions.  The  desire  changes  the 
direction  of  thought,  when  consciousness  is  open,  expectant. 

The  general  feeling  tone  of  faith  is  excitement-repose,  running 
the  gamut  from  the  highest  ecstasy  and  pure  joy  to  deep  peace  and 
the  waiting  stillness.  The  factor  which  brings  emotions  of  this 
class  is  apparently  the  oneness  of  the  individual  and  the  source 
from  which  the  desire  is  to  be  realized.  Brahmanism  teaches  that 
the  highest  bliss  is  complete  absorption  in  the  Nirvana.  The  author 
of  the  fourteenth  chapter  of  the  gospel  of  St.  John  sums  up  the 
teaching  on  the  unity  of  God  and  man  in  the  following  expression : 
''I  am  in  the  Father  and  ye  in  me,  and  I  in  you."  This  is  to 
bring  the  highest  satisfaction  and  the  greatest  power.  James  says 
that  this  is  the  appeal  in  all  movements  which  have  meant  much 
to  humanity,  i.e.,  kinship  or  oneness. 

"If  we  survey  the  field  of  history  and  ask  what  feature  all 
great  periods  of  revival,  of  expansion  of  the  human  mind,  display 
in  common,  we  shall  find  I  think,  simply  this:  that  each  and  all 
of  them  have  said  to  the  human  being.  'The  inmost  nature  of  the 
reality  is  congenial  to  powers  which  you  possess. '  " 9 

All  this  contains  an  important  lesson  for  religious  propaganda. 
That  concept  of  God  has  the  strongest  appeal  which  makes  the 
worshipper  feel  that  he  is  akin  to  God  or  that  God  is  akin  to  him. 
The  strong  appeal  of  Christianty  is  that  the  tie  or  relationship  be- 
tween God  and  man  is  love  of  such  a  nature  that  it  defines  expect- 
ancy and  removes  all  doubts  as  to  the  future  outcome  of  events, 
therefore  bringing  the  satisfaction  and  peace  sought.  To  disbelieve 
in  a  God  who  has  this  intimate  relationship  to  us  seems  the  acme  of 
evil  or  sin  from  the  standpoint  of  this  religion,  the  greatest  dis- 
loyalty to  life  itself.  To  believe  in  such  a  God  is  an  essential  fac- 
tor in  salvation  and  the  highest  service  man  has  in  his  power  to 
render  to  himself,  to  others  and  to  the  universe  and  its  God.  Love 
is  the  culmination  of  faith. 

The  feeling  of  kinship,  commonly  called  rapport,  is  likewise  of 
the  utmost  importance  in  all  physical  cures  where  faith  plays  a 
part.  It  is  the  consensus  of  opinion  among  psychoanalysts  that 
cure  by  their  method  is  only  possible  where  the  rapport  exists. 
One  of  them  at  least  believes  that  the  establishing  of  this  bond  is 
sometimes  sufficient  to  effect  the  cure  without  the  analysis.  A 

•  Morton  Prince,  The  Unconscious,  pp.  368-9,  p.  500. 
»  Op.  cit.,  p.  86. 


22  THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Christian  Science  healer  told  me  that  she  could  not  help  anyone 
who  was  antagonistic  to  her  and  that  she  believed  this  was  the  com- 
mon experience  of  all  healers.  A  well  known  medical  writer  after 
describing  the  rather  elaborate  Weir  Mitchell  rest  cure,  concludes 
that  the  good  results  sometimes  attained  are  chiefly  brought  about 
by  the  suggestive  influence  of  the  physician  and  that  the  main  effect 
of  the  treatment  is  mental,  much  depending  on  the  personality  of 
the  physician  and  on  the  individuality  of  the  patient.  I  do  not 
entirely  agree  with  this,  but  certain  it  is  that  a  feeling  of  close 
fellowship  brings  about  a  state  of  mental  and  physical  relaxation 
essential  to  the  healing  of  the  body  and  to  the  redirection  of  nerve 
energy. 

What  is  the  function  and  value  of  faith  in  human  life  can  be 
pretty  well  made  out  from  the  foregoing.  Religious  writings  of  all 
times  and  places  abound  in  stories  of  men  whose  lives  have  been 
changed  and  reinvigorated  by  repentance  and  consequent  acts  of 
faith.  It  means  either  a  tapping  of  our  own  reserves  of  energy  or 
the  drawing  upon  the  sources  of  divine  energy.  "They  that  wait 
upon  the  Lord  shall  renew  their  strength."  Everyone  has  the 
option  of  believing  that  which  harmonizes  best  with  his  own  ex- 
perience. History  will  show,  I  believe,  that  the  men  who  have  most 
influenced  the  race  through  the  force  of  their  personality  have 
been  men  who  were  great  practisers  of  prayer,  or  else  had  a  strong 
belief  in  destiny.  One  who  believes  in  destiny  is  one  who  takes 
some  sort  of  an  appeal  to  the  dispenser  of  fate  in  such  a  way  that 
he  is  confident  of  his  own  powers  of  accomplishment  and  hence 
undertakes  and  carries  through  tremendous  tasks.  Likewise  we 
have  found  it  to  be  a  restorer  of  physical  power  and  health.  Just 
as  we  found  repentance  necessary  for  spiritual  rebirth,  so  we  find 
relaxation  necessary  for  bodily  renewal.  Some  physician  has  said: 
"The  primary  effect  of  relaxation  is  weakness,  stupor,  numbness 
and  death-like  paralysis ;  the  secondary  effect,  however,  is  increased 
strength  and  new  life." 

The  important  question,  the  practical  question  in  the  whole 
matter  is,  are  the  faith  processes  something  common  to  all,  or  is 
there  a  class  of  people  who  have  the  gift  of  faith  as  some  have  the 
gift  of  music  or  art?  It  is  peculiar  to  some  people,  no  doubt,  to 
excel  in  the  exercise  of  faith,  but  if  our  reasoning  has  been  correct, 
we  can  all  cultivate  it  in  the  measure  that  our  individual  lives  call 
for  it.  First  of  all,  we  must  have  desire  to  realize  an  ideal;  it  is 
the  first  step  in  the  faith  process.  Desire  is  a  mental  process  which 
can  not  either  be  completely  rationalized  or  find  expression  in  will 
processes.  Hence  its  importance  in  consciousness  is  overlooked  but 


A  PARTIAL  ANALYSIS  OF  FAITH  23 

it  is  the  first  step  in  all  other  processes,  speaking  broadly.  In  the 
case  of  faith,  the  desires  are  those  which  enter  into  the  stream  of 
consciousness  and  begin  to  function  as  a  part  of  it,  without  being 
completely  rationalized  or  motivated.  And  herein  lies  the  danger 
of  faith:  that  one  gives  the  reins  to  desire  without  waiting  for  a 
reasonable  outcome  to  be  forecasted,  when  such  an  outcome  is 
within  the  possibilities  of  reason.  It  is  this  abuse  of  faith  which 
has  brought  it  into  discredit.  Faith  should  only  be  called  into 
play  where  strong  desire  exists  and  reason  fails. 

Secondly  to  attain  an  effectual  faith,  one  must  cultivate  harmony 
within  oneself,  a  sort  of  rapport  between  the  subconscious  and  the 
surface  consciousness,  so  that  the  forces  of  both  work  together  in 
greater  power  than  either  alone  could  possess.  Mystics  and  healers 
alike  emphasize  this  need  of  harmony,  the  absence  of  any  distracting 
thought  which  might  draw  off  energy  in  a  useless  and  harmful  ex- 
penditure. A  physician  in  speaking  of  the  over-reaction  of  certain 
patients  to  incoming  stimuli  of  all  kinds,  says:  "Such  patients  are 
consequently  in  a  state  of  perpetual  mental  unrest.  .  .  .  Nervous 
energy  is  being  wasted  at  a  terrific  rate  in  all  directions. ' ' 10  Another 
physician  speaks  of  the  conservation  and  direction  of  energy,  say- 
ing: "In  the  well  developed  individual  the  distribution  of  energy 
through  widening  of  the  symbol,  the  'soul'  or  spiritual  development 
has  left  the  proper  amount  of  functioning,  of  energy  carriage,  on  any 
one  of  them. ' '  " 

In  the  same  way,  if  one  is  to  exercise  faith  by  way  of  suggestion 
for  the  benefit  of  another,  one  must  practise  removing  all  antagonism 
between  the  suggestionist  and  the  one  who  is  to  profit  thereby.  The 
cultivation  of  a  spirit  of  love  and  kindness  is  the  cardinal  teaching 
of  the  great  religions  and  they  abound  in  precepts  and  admonitions 
for  doing  this.  The  only  general  principle  that  comes  to  mind  that 
would  be  of  aid  in  this,  is  the  recognition  of  kinship  with  one's 
fellow  men  as  spoken  of  above,  the  abolition  of  all  class  and  racial 
distinction  where  moral  matters  are  concerned.  Spiritual  faith  seems 
to  rest,  by  the  same  law,  on  the  recognition  of  the  identity  of  one's 
desire  and  purpose  with  those  of  the  God  of  the  universe. 

The  third  rule  for  the  attainment  of  faith  is  that  one  is  to  become 
skillful  in  inhibiting  the  stream  of  thought,  in  the  power  of  relax- 
ing, in  reaching  monoideism,  by  a  process  of  letting  go  all  ideas  in 
consciousness  in  order  for  the  one  coming  from  another  source  to 

10 Bryant,  "  Treatment  of  The  Chronic  Intestinal  Invalid,"  Am.  Jour,  of 
The  Med.  Soc.,  Jan.  1921,  p.  72. 

11  Jelliffe,  ' '  Multiple  Sclerosis  and  Psychoanalysis, ' '  Am.  Jour,  of  The  Med. 
Soc.,  May,  1921,  p.  672. 


24  THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOl'll  Y 

hold  its  place  in  the  focus  of  a  new  consciousness.  A  similar  relaxa- 
tion of  the  body  is  a  help  in  this.  The  celebrated  Reverend  Dr. 

T ,  the  first  and  greatest  successor  of  Moody,  once  told  a  small 

group  of  listeners  that  he  often  spent  the  night  in  prayer  lying  prone, 
which  is  the  attitude  of  greatest  bodily  relaxation.  Medical  men  are 
coming  to  realize  the  function  of  physical  relaxation  in  restorative 
processes.  One  of  them  says  that  relaxation  for  nervousness  may  be 
like  diet  or  hygienic  measures  in  gastro-intestinal  disorders,  and  that 
doing  away  with  residual  tension  is  the  sine  qua  non  of  thorough 
and  successful  treatment.  "So  in  certain  chronic  cases,  relaxation 
becomes  a  gradual  progress,  a  matter  of  habit  formation,  wherein 
the  presence  of  pain  or  disordered  intestinal  secretions  or  other 
organic  disturbances  may  completely  block  the  way."  " 

In  a  word,  while  we  shall  never  rationalize  the  supreme  and  per- 
sistent content  of  our  highest  faith,  we  do  rationalize  much  of  the 
humbler  sort.  We  shall  never  understand  the  great  geniuses  of  faith 
any  more  than  we  do  the  great  geniuses  in  music  or  philosophy,  but 
we  may  by  faithful  effort  learn  something  of  its  laws  as  we  do  those 
of  memory  or  judgment,  and  in  a  small  way  grow  in  the  knowledge 
and  practise  thereof. 

LUCINDA  PEARL  BOGOS. 

UBBANA,  ILL. 

BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  Psychology  of  the  Special  Senses  and  their  Functional  Dis- 
orders. ARTHUR  F.  HURST.  (The  Croonian  Lectures.)  Oxford 
University  Press.  1920.  Pp.  122. 

The  title  of  this  book  is  somewhat  misleading,  as  it  deals  almost 
entirely  with  functional  disorders  of  the  special  senses.  There  is  an 
introductory  chapter  on  the  nature  of  hysteria,  followed  by  chapters 
on  disturbances  of  the  special  senses,  especially  of  touch,  pain,  hear- 
ing and  vision.  These  disturbances  are  in  the  nature  of  anaesthesias 
and  hyperaesthesias. 

All  sensory  experiences  are  considered  as  active  processes,  as 
"reactions"  of  the  individual,  rather  than  as  the  mere  passive  recep- 
tion of  stimuli.  In  the  absence  of  this  active  process,  the  state  of 
attention,  no  impressions  will  produce  sensory  experiences.  In  order 
to  hear,  one  must  listen ;  in  order  to  see,  one  must  look.  This  active 
process  has  its  physiological  basis  in  synaptic  changes  in  the  afferent 
neural  pathways;  attention  is  lowered  resistance,  absence  of  atten- 

i*  Jacobus,  "  Reduction  of  Nervous  Irritability  and  Excitement  through  Pro- 
gressive Relaxation,"  Jour,  of  Nervous  and  Mental  Diseases,  April,  1921,  p.  284. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  25 

tion  is  increased  resistance.  Any  condition  which  will  increase  atten- 
tion to  a  group  of  sensory  stimuli  may  produce  hyperaesthesia,  and 
any  condition  which  will  decrease  attention  will  produce  lowered 
sensitivity  or  even  anaesthesia. 

Now  suggestion  is  a  very  potent  factor  in  producing  these 
changes  and  is  made  responsible  for  all  of  the  functional  sensory 
disorders.  Hysteria  is  defined  as  a  ''condition  in  which  symptoms 
are  present  which  have  resulted  from  suggestion  and  are  curable 
by  psychotherapy"  (p.  5).  Many  of  the  supposedly  fixed  stigmata 
of  hysteria  such  as  the  ansesthesias  and  the  restricted  visual  fields 
are  suggested  unintentionally  by  the  examining  physician.  The 
patient  being  led  by  the  technique  of  the  examination  and  by  lead- 
ing questions  to  believe  that  certain  conditions  are  present,  e.g. 
anaesthesias,  fails  to  pay  further  attention  to  their  sensory  stimuli. 
The  uniformity  of  the  symptoms  in  different  cases  is  attributed  to 
the  uniformity  of  examination  methods  with  the  consequent  similar 
heterosuggestion.  The  hysterical  phenomena  which  are  not  the  direct 
effect  of  heterosuggestion  are  the  result  of  autosuggestion  following 
organic  disabilities.  Thus  a  soldier  deafened  by  a  shell  explosion  may 
believe  that  he  is  permanently  deafened,  and  will  no  longer  listen. 
Hence  he  may  remain  deaf  after  all  organic  disturbance  has  ceased. 

By  forced  attention  to  the  pain  of  wounds,  the  patient  may 
become  so  accustomed  to  "look  for"  the  pain  that  he  may  feel  it  long 
after  the  wound  has  completely  healed.  Here  the  sensory  experiences 
are  the  result  of  greatly  lowered  synaptic  resistance. 

Upon  the  foregoing  conception  of  hysteria  the  author  with  his 
associates  has  effected  many  cures  of  functional  disorders  among  the 
soldiers.  A  group  of  case  histories'  is  presented  to  illustrate  each 
type  of  hysterical  symptom.  The  most  effective  treatment,  where  the 
intelligence  of  the  patient  permits,  consists  of  a  simple  and  clear 
explanation  of  the  facts  of  suggestion,  with  a  course  of  training  in 
the  active  process  of  listening,  looking,  and  feeling. 

A.   T.   POFFENBERGER. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

SCIENTIA.  August,  1921.  De  la  contribution  des  divers  pays 
au  developpement  de  la  chimie  (pp.  85-102)  :  B.  L.  VANZETTI 
(Padua). -A  well-written  sketch  of  a  complex  history,  with  insis- 
tence on  its  international  character.  The  Relation  of  Light  Emis- 
sion and  Absorption  to  Atomic  Structure  (pp.  103-114)  :  E.  P. 
LEWIS  (California).- A  notable  effort  to  put  in  brief  and  simple 


26         THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

form  the  tangled  and  still  highly  problematic  current  conceptions 
of  the  structure  of  atoms.  The  result  is  a  paper  well  worth  careful 
perusal.  Le  problems  de  I'integration  physiologique  (pp.  115- 
126):  C.  M.  CHILD  (Chicago). -Restates  the  author's  well-known 
opinions.  The  chemically  most  active  region  of  an  organism  tends 
to  dominate  the  rest,  because  of  the  influences  which  that  chemical 
activity  sends  out.  Dominance  and  subordination  can  thus  be 
chemically  explained  and  quantitatively  studied.  ProbUmes  finan- 
ciers d'apres  guerre.  III.  D'un  nouveau  princvpe  de  progressivite 
pour  les  impots  de  succession,  (pp.  127-144) :  CORRADO  GINI 
(Padua). -An  interesting  detailed  and  critical  study  of  the  pro- 
posal to  tax  inheritances  more  severely  in  proportion  to  the  number 
of  generations  through  which  the  heritage  has  descended.  In  the 
present  financial  crisis,  the  author  recommends  heavy  taxes  on  such 
capital  as  is  not  due  to  the  labor  and  savings  of  the  present  owner, 
and  likewise  on  consumption  which  is  beyond  what  is  necessary 
for  efficiency.  Reviews  of  Scientific  Books  and  Periodicals. 

Bruhn,  Wilhelm.    Glauben  and  Wissen.    Leipzig  and  Berlin :  B.  G. 

Teubner.    1921.    Pp.  108.    Kart.  30c;  geb.  35c. 
Dilthey,    Wilhelm.     Die    Jugendgeschichte    Hegels,    und    Andere 

Abhandlungen  zur  Geschichte  des  Deutschen  Idealismus.    Gesam- 

melte  Schriften.     Band  IV.     Leipzig:   B.   G.   Teubner.     1921. 

Pp.  x  +  583.    $2.05,  geheftet ;  $2.25,  gebunden. 
W.  Dilthey,  A.  Riehl,  W.  Wundt,  H.  Ebbinghaus,  R.  Eucken,  Br. 

Bauch,  Th.  Litt,  M.  Geiger,  T.  K.  Oesterreich.     Sytematische 

Philosophic.    Edited  by  Paul  Hinneberg.    Third,  revised  edition. 

Leipzig :  B.  G.  Teubner.    1921.    Pp.  x  +  408. 
Hartman,  Nicolai.     Grundziige  einer  Metaphysik  der  Erkenntnis. 

Berlin  and  Leipzig :  Walter  de  Gruyter  &  Co.    1921.    Pp.  xii  -j- 

389. 

Stolzle,  Remigius.     Charles  Darwins  Stellung  zum  Gottesglauben. 
Leipzig :  Felix  Meiner.    1922.    Pp.  34.   Brosch.    25c. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

fiMILE  BOUTROUX 

fimile  Boutroux  died  in  Paris  on  November  22  at  the  age  of 
seventy-six  years.  This  simple  announcement  came  as  a  shock  to  the 
many  academic  generations  that  have  passed  through  the  Sorbonne 
since  Boutroux  first  became  professor  of  philosophy  in  1885,  and  to 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  27 

the  countless  friends  his  lucid  lectures  and  his  charming  personality 
won  for  him  in  England  and  America.  To  the  students  and  profes- 
sors of  philosophy  in  France,  to  whom,  from  Bergson  down,  he  has 
been  cher  mattre,  Boutroux  seemed  a  fixed  star,  and  a  star  of  the 
first  magnitude.  His  passing  means  the  removal  of  a  thinker  and  a 
man  whose  influence  over  the  present  generation  of  educated  French- 
men has  been  very  great,  not  only  through  his  original  philosophic 
analysis  of  the  basic  conceptions  of  science,  but  even  more  through 
his  gift  of  sympathetic  interpretation  of  the  great  philosophers  of 
the  past. 

It  is  perhaps  as  an  illuminating  teacher  that  Boutroux  will  be 
longest  remembered.  He  possessed  that  ability  that  seems  the  gift 
of  certain  French  minds,  and  that  is  the  envy  and  the  despair  of 
foreign  admirers,  to  transcend  the  explication  des  textes  and  to  grasp 
the  very  soul  of  a  man 's  thought.  He  aimed,  in  his  own  words,  ' '  to 
seek  the  truth  together  with  a  great  philosopher,  following  him  along 
the  winding  bypaths  of  meditation,  sharing  in  his  emotions,  enjoy- 
ing with  him  that  harmony  wherein  his  mind  has  found  repose." 
Unfortunately,  unlike  Faguet,  there  did  not  flow  from  his  pen  an 
unending  series  of  penetrating  recreations  of  the  thinkers  of  the  past. 
We  have  a  single  volume  of  studies  on  Socrates,  Aristotle,  Kant; 
and  we  have  his  Pascal.  But  the  memory  of  his  lectures  on  the  his- 
tory of  philosophy  at  the  Bcole  Normale  Superieure  and  at  the  Sor- 
bonne  will  not  soon  fade,  nor  will  his  art  be  forgotten. 

In  his  original  thinking  Boutroux  addressed  himself  to  the  prob- 
lem around  which  has  resolved  so  much  of  French  philosophical 
investigation  in  the  last  generation,  the  problem  of  liberty.  In  a 
world  of  ordered  uniformity  and  law,  such  as  the  scientific  advance 
of  the  last  century  has  demanded,  where  is  there  to  be  found  room 
for  that  moral  choice  without  which  ethics,  and  indeed  any  human 
activity,  even  that  of  science  itself,  seems  impossible?  From  1874, 
when  his  doctor's  thesis  De  la  contingence  des  lois  de  la  nature 
appeared,  to  Science  et  Religion  in  1908,  Boutroux  undertook  a  criti- 
cism and  an  evaluation  of  the  fundamental  conceptions  of  mechan- 
istic science  in  the  interests  of  revealing  the  discontinuities  and  the 
contingencies  that  lie  at  its  very  heart.  Probably  his  most  important 
book  is  his  De  I'idee  de  loi  naturelle,  published  in  1894,  wherein  his 
analysis  is  at  its  best.  Here  he  tries  to  establish  the  difference  between 
the  various  kinds  of  laws  which  the  particular  sciences  have  dis- 
covered, and  especially  between  the  static  and  mathematical  laws  of 
mechanics,  physics,  and  chemistry,  and  the  dynamic  and  qualitative 
laws  of  the  biological  and  social  sciences.  The  latter  alone  deal  with 
concrete  realities;  the  former  are  abstractions  which  represent  but 


28  THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

one  aspect  of  physical  events,  that  susceptible  of  definite  measure- 
ment. These  mechanical  and  mathematical  laws,  it  is  true,  are  neces- 
sary, and  set  rigid  limits  to  the  events  that  are  possible;  but  they 
leave  undetermined  the  particular  things  to  whose  activity  they  set 
limits.  Just  what  that  activity  will  be  depends  on  the  laws  of  living, 
of  dynamic,  ever-changing  things,  which  are  too  close  to  reality  to  be 
purely  mechanical. 

Boutroux  insists  strongly,  following  Comte,  on  the  independence 
of  each  science,  and  on  the  irreducibility  of  its  laws  to  those  of  any 
other  science.  The  laws  of  the  more  concrete  sciences,  like  psychology 
and  biology,  can  not  be  deduced  from  those  of  the  more  abstract  and 
mathematical  sciences ;  each  new  realm  is  governed  by  new  and  special 
principles  not  contained  in  those  of  the  previous  realm.  Nor  is  a 
complex  whole  no  more  than  the  sum  of  its  parts;  such  a  whole  is 
genuinely  creative,  for  with  it  new  qualities  come  into  existence.  The 
free  development  of  such  new  wholes  Boutroux  believes  to  be  the 
truly  active  and  contingent  part  of  nature. 

But  the  little  that  remains  to  us  in  written  form  of  Boutroux  is 
by  no  means  the  measure  of  his  influence.  It  was  the  charm  of  his 
personality  that  carried  his  message  so  far.  To  know  him  was  to  love 
him.  We  need  go  no  further  than  our  own  William  James,  who  never 
mentions  Boutroux  in  his  letters  save  to  call  him  "a  regular  angel" 
or  "the  gentlest  and  most  lovable  of  characters."  And  it  is  surely 
as  the  teacher  of  the  youth  he  so  well  loved  that  Boutroux  would  most 
wish  to  be  remembered. 

JOHN  H.  RANDALL,  JR. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  2.  JANUARY  19,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


AN  ANALYSIS  OF  REFLECTIVE  THOUGHT 

IN  replying  to  Mr.  Buermeyer's  criticism  of  my  analysis  of  reflec- 
tive thought1  I  suffer  from  somewhat  the  same  embarrassment 
that  affected  him  in  writing  it.  He  was  handicapped  by  the  fact 
that  the  analysis  which  he  takes  as  the  subject  of  his  criticism  was 
written  for  pedagogical  purposes  rather  than  for  strictly  logical  ends. 
I  am  handicapped  in  replying  by  the  fact  that  since  Mr.  Buermeyer 
states  that  he  accepts  the  general  instrumental  position,  and  since 
he  develops  his  own  views  incidentally  in  a  criticism  of  portions  of 
How  We  Think,  I  am  not  always  quite  sure  of  what  his  exact  posi- 
tion would  be  were  he  writing  to  express  his  independent  beliefs. 
In  any  case  I  shall  ignore  the  statements  of  How  We  Think,  and 
attempt  to  discuss  the  points  made  in  Mr.  Buermeyer's  article  on 
their  own  merits.  It  hardly  seems  to  me  that  the  original  text 
naturally  bears  in  all  points  the  construction  he  puts  upon  it,  but 
that  is  a  minor  matter,  and  if  as  acute  a  critic  as  Mr.  Buermeyer 
misunderstood  it,  the  text  is  hardly  likely  to  have  been  unambiguous 
to  others.  So  I  am  grateful  to  him  for  this  opportunity. 

The  questions  raised  by  Mr.  Buermeyer  concern  the  matter  of 
steps  or  processes  of  thoughts.  Starting  from  my  analysis  into 
(i)  the  occurrence  of  a  problem,  (ii)  its  specification,  (iii)  occur- 
rence of  a  solving  suggestion,  or  supposition,  hypothesis,  (iv)  elabo- 
ration of  suggestion,  or  reasoning,  (v)  experimental  testing,  he 
adduces  reasons  for  holding  that  the  reflective  act  can  not  be 
resolved  into  separate  steps,  and  that,  especially  as  thinking  be- 
comes more  competent  or  scientific,  the  second,  third  and  fourth 
"tend  to  fuse  into  one  indissoluble  act."  Part  of  Mr.  Buermeyer's 
contention  I  accept  unreservedly,  and  am  chagrined  to  find  that  I 
should  have  given  any  impression  to  the  contrary.  In  speaking  of 
"steps"  it  is  perhaps  natural  to  suppose  that  something  chrono- 
logical is  intended,  and  from  that  it  is  presumably  a  natural  conclu- 
sion that  the  steps  are  taken  in  a  temporal  sequence  in  the  order  taken 

iThis  JOURNAL,  VoL  XVII,  pp.  673-681. 

29 


30  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

above.  Nothing  of  this  sort,  however,  is  intended.  The  analysis  is 
formal,  and  indicates  the  logical  "movements"  involved  in  an  act  of 
critical  thought.  It  is  a  matter  of  indifference  which  comes  first. 
Not  even  the  occurrence  of  a  problem  need  come  absolutely  first  in 
time.  For  a  scientific  man  may  reason  and  experiment  for  the  ex- 
press purpose  of  discovering  a  problem  upon  which  to  exercise  in- 
quiry. Were  I  writing  at  the  present  time  and  writing  a  complete 
statement,  I  should  certainly  emphasize  the  point  that  the  main 
distinction  between  uncritical  and  critical  or  scientific  thinking  is 
that  the  latter  strives  to  combine  as  far  as  possible  into  one  act  the 
functions  of  inferring  and  testing.  The  attempt  represents  an  ideal 
or  limit  which  can  not  be  attained  except  in  mathematics.  But  so 
far  as  the  endeavor  is  concerned,  I  accept  not  merely  Mr.  Buer- 
meyer's  criticism  of  temporal  separation  of  steps,  but  his  conclusion 
regarding  the  fusion  into  one  process  of  induction,  deduction  and 
experimental  testing. 

Apparently  this  statement  leaves  no  outstanding  differences  be- 
tween Mr.  Buermeyer  and  myself.  However,  the  case  is  not  so 
simple  as  this.  Mr.  Buermeyer  says  things  which  imply  that  in 
denying  temporal  separation  he  also  denies  any  significant  distinc- 
tion of  functions,  while  I  still  stand  by  the  indispensable  nature  for 
logical  analysis  of  these  distinctions.  Upon  this  point,  however,  the 
embarrassment  to  which  I  referred  in  the  opening  sentences  comes 
into  play.  I  am  not  sure  just  how  far  he  means  to  go  in  the  direc- 
tion of  logical  as  well  as  of  psychological  identification.  In  any 
<ase,  he  makes  specific  statements  which  point  to  obliteration  of 
•distinctions  in  logic  between  induction  and  deduction,  and  those 
statements  will  be  used  by  me  to  clear  up  what  seem  to  me  signif- 
icant logical  distinctions.  He  refers  indeed  pretty  continually  to 
the  functions  of  induction,  deduction  and  experiment,  in  the  course 
of  showing  their  mutual  involution.  But  whether  this  reference 
marks  a  recognition  that  induction,  deduction  and  experiment  are 
logically  distinct  from  one  another  or  whether  it  is  a  mere  conces- 
sion on  Mr.  Buermeyer 's  part  to  the  exigencies  of  stating  my  own 
position  for  purposes  of  criticism,  I  am  not  sure. 

This  question  is  the  important  one,  for  it  concerns  the  respective 
definitions  of  induction  and  deduction.  My  impression  is  that  Mr. 
Buermeyer  accepts  the  traditional  statement  of  induction  and  deduc- 
tion as  logically  movements  respectively  from  the  particular  to  the 
general  and  from  the  general  to  the  particular.  My  chief  concern  is 
to  modify  this  tradition.  Induction  I  take  to  be  a  movement  from 
•  facts  to  meaning;  deduction  a  development  of  meanings,  an  exhibi- 
tion of  implications,  while  I  hold  that  the  connection  between  fact 


AN  ANALYSIS  OF  REFLECTIVE  THOUGHT     31 

and  meaning  is  made  only  by  an  act  in  the  ordinary  physical  sense 
of  the  word  act,  that  is,  by  experiment  involving  movement  of  the 
body  and  change  in  surrounding  conditions.  These  are  the  points 
to  which  I  hold,  surrendering  to  Mr.  Buermeyer  as  unclear  and 
inadequate  those  portions  of  How  We  Think  calculated  to  leave  any 
other  impression.  There  are  of  course  points  of  contact  between 
the  traditional  statement  and  that  which  I  have  just  made.  Facts, 
data,  are  logically  speaking  particulars,  while  meaning  functions  as 
a  universal.  But  the  traditional  discussion  takes  either  particular 
or  universal  or  both  for  granted  as  given,  while  I  am  trying  to 
account  for  them,  and  to  account  for  them  in  terms  of  the  reflective 
transformation  of  an  experienced  situation  from  a  confused  and 
uncertain  state  to  a  clear  and  coherent  condition.  In  this  process, 
data  with  their  particularistic  function  present  themselves  when  the 
situation  is  subjected  to  analytic  observation;  they  represent  the 
attempt  to  specify  the  problem.  Suggested  meanings  present  them- 
selves as  the  means  of  restoring  unity,  coherence  and  consistency 
to  the  particulars.  As  such  they  have  the  function  of  universality. 
Experiment  is  the  indicated  application  of  meanings  to  the  partic- 
ulars to  see  what  happens — to  see  whether  the  suggested  unification 
can  be  carried  out  and  maintained.  Experiment  has  a  two-fold 
function.  From  the  side  of  suggested  meanings  it  is  a  test ;  from  the 
side  of  the  otherwise  fragmentary  data,  it  supplies  organization, 
system.  There  are  various  things  in  Mr.  Buermeyer 's  criticism  which 
indicate  that  he  accepts  the  traditional  idea  of  ready-made  or  given 
particulars  and  universals,  data  and  meanings.  At  this  point,  we 
part  company. 

The  explicit  discussion  of  induction  and  deduction  may  con- 
veniently begin  with  a  reference  to  the  fact  that  the  foregoing  state- 
ments assume  but  three  functions;  while  the  one  quoted  earlier  in- 
cludes four — leaving  out  the  problem  in  respect  to  which  there  is  no 
difference  between  us.  This  seeming  discrepancy  is  due  to  the  fact 
that  the  text  of  How  We  Think,  with  its  practical  pedagogic  aim, 
was  especially  concerned  with  enforcing  the  difference  between  un- 
critical and  critical  thinking.2  Now  one  of  the  most  marked  dif- 
ferences between  poor  thinking  and  good  thinking  is  the  former's 
premature  acceptance  and  assertion  of  suggested  meanings.  One  of 
the  marks  of  controlled  thinking  is  postponement  of  such  acceptance. 
Consequently  I  inserted  between  the  problem  and  the  presentation 
of  a  suggestion  the  requirement  of  analytic  examination  of  the  "facts 

2  The  reader  should  not  be  misled  by  the  fact  that  Mr.  Buermeyer  and  I 
use  the  word  "  reasoning  "  differently.  He  uses  it  to  express  what  I  call 
critical  or  reflective  thinking — thinking  in  its  eulogistic  sense.  I  prefer  to  con- 
fine it  to  "  ratiocination  "  or  rational  discourse,  the  elaboration  of  implications. 


32  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  the  case."  This  "step"  is  not  however  different  in  critical  think- 
ing from  the  step  of  a  tentative  or  hypothetical  adoption  of  a  sugges- 
tion. It  marks  the  endeavor  to  control  the  form  which  a  hypothe- 
tical meaning  takes.  The  point  as  regards  my  view  of  induction 
can  be  made  clearer  by  distinguishing  between  the  inductive  move- 
ment and  induction  as  a  critically  executed  function.  Both  termi- 
nate logically  in  an  hypothesis.  But  in  ordinary  thinking  no  pains 
are  taken  to  control  the  formation  of  the  hypothesis.  In  critical  or 
scientific  inquiry  great  pains  are  taken  to  secure  an  accurate  speci- 
fication and  collection  of  observed  data  as  the  means  of  control. 
This  "step"  is  in  my  opinion  the  characteristic  trait  of  scientific 
induction.  There  is  no  implication  that  suggestions  do  not  arise 
until  this  step  is  taken.  On  the  contrary  suggestions  swarm  and 
press  for  acceptance.  That  is  the  very  danger  against  which  sys- 
tematically executed  analytic  observation  protects  us. 

Mill  set  out  to  lay  down  rules  for  induction  which  shall  be  as 
stringent  as  syllogistic  rules  were  for  Aristotelian  deduction.  Now 
as  against  this  point  of  view  it  seems  to  me  essential  to  maintain 
that  the  occurrence  to  the  mind  of  explanatory  "causes"  is  not  a 
matter  which  can  ever  be  subjected  to  stringent  rules.  The  elements 
of  individual  capacity  and  of  accident  can  never  be  excluded  in 
the  inductive  operation.  Huxley  remarks  that  after  reading  Darwin 
and  Wallace  their  theory  of  the  origin  of  species  seemed  so  obvious 
that  he  could  only  wonder  how  he  and  others  who  had  access  to  the 
same  facts  should  not  have  thought  of  such  an  obvious  explanation. 
Here  is  the  factor  which  can  not  be  reduced  to  rule  as  Mill  set  out 
to  reduce  it.  But  on  the  other  hand,  a  certain  degree  of  regulation 
of  occurrence  of  hypotheses  does  obviously  occur.  How  t  The  reply 
of  How  We  Think,  to  which  I  still  hold,  is  that  the  analytic  examina- 
tion (extensive  and  intensive)  of  observed  events  supplies  such 
control  as  is  available.  This  process  can  be  reduced  to  a  considerable 
extent  to  rules.  Mill's  "canons"  are  not  what  he  took  them  to  be,  but 
they  are,  especially  the  method  of  Difference  and  the  Joint  Method, 
statements  of  the  way  to  conduct  observation  in  order  to  secure  the 
data  which  are  most  likely  to  render  the  suggestion  of  meaning  (hy- 
pothesis, theory,  "cause")  relevant  and  fruitful — "most  likely," 
other  things  being  equal.  There  is  no  guarantee  like  that  of  the 
Aristotelian  syllogism  such  as  Mill  aspired  to. 

Instead  of  ruling  out  Mill's  contribution  to  the  theory  of  induc- 
tion I  tried  to  place  it  where  it  belongs.  This  consideration  supplies 
my  answer  to  Mr.  Buermeyer's  remark  that  my  account  leaves  me 
without  the  support  of  Mill's  canons,  and  in  general  reduces  induc- 
tion to  a  mere  matter  of  happy  guessing.  Just  because  the  phase 


AN  ANALYSIS  OF  REFLECTIVE  THOUGHT     33 

of  happy  guessing  can  not  be  eliminated,  specification  of  the  nature 
of  the  problem  or  analytic  observation  is  of  transcendent  importance 
in  induction.  The  performance  of  analytic  observation  of  course 
involves  experiment;  it  does  not  precede  it.  And  it  is  guided  by 
some  idea  or  suggestion  in  most  cases.  Nevertheless  there  is  a  logical 
difference  between  experiment  as  resulting  in  data  which  affect  the 
formation  of  a  hypothesis  and  as  affecting  its  acceptance.  This  is 
true  even  when  the  same  experiment  has  as  matter  of  fact  both  effects. 
Hence  I  can  not  accept  Mr.  Buermeyer's  emendation  that  instead 
of  defining  scientific  induction  as  the  sum  of  processes  by  which 
formation  of  explanatory  conceptions  is  facilitated  (and  regulated) 
it  should  be  defined  as  those  by  which  their  acceptance  is  determined. 
Logically,  we  must  distinguish  the  two  results,  although  practically 
(as  has  been  said)  the  ideal  or  limit  of  scientific  method  is  that  the 
same  concrete  procedure  should  effect  both  of  them. 

This  is  not  a  matter  of  splitting  hairs.  Practically  it  is  essential 
in  order  that  the  hypothetic  character  of  an  explanatory  conception 
may  be  adequately  apprehended;  and  that  the  one  thinking  may 
make  certain  that  a  proving  or  testing  experiment  brings  to  light 
other  facts  than  those  which  have  led  to  its  formation  and  (tenta- 
tive) adoption.  One  has  only  to  read  current  literature  on  spiritual- 
ism and  interpretation  of  dreams,  proceeding  from  men  who  have 
established  scientific  reputations  in  other  fields,  to  note  the  practical 
importance  of  this  discrimination.  The  history  of  science  is  full 
of  similar  cases — such  as  the  elaboration  of  Weissmannism. 

The  theoretical  bearing  of  insistence  upon  induction  as  connected 
with  hypothesizing  may  be  seen  by  examining  Mr.  Buermeyer's 
contention  that  it  is  ' '  at  least  equally  deductive  in  character. "  I  do 
not  differ  from  Mr.  Buermeyer  in  holding  that  it  will  be  adequately 
performed  in  the  degree  in  which  it  utilizes  deduction.  But  this 
statement  implies  that  they  are  logically  distinct,  while  Mr.  Buer- 
meyer goes  to  the  extent  of  holding  that  they  are  identical.  Deduc- 
tion involves  as  he  points  out  "the  application  of  knowledge,  of  ideas 
already  in  hand"  (p.  675).  Now  this  he  claims  shows  that  forming 
a  hypothesis  is  deductive,  since  it  rests  upon  prior  knowledge.  "Only 
if  we  already  have  some  information  about  a  problematic  situation, 
some  experience  of  analogous  situations,  are  we  able  to  form  a 
conjecture  not  wholly  random"  (p.  675).  And  again  he  speaks  of 
the  competent  thinker  as  the  one  who  ' '  focuses  upon  the  case  in  ques- 
tion all  the  funded  results  of  the  agent's  past  experience,  the  occur- 
rence of  analogies  at  once  subtle  and  to  the  point"  (p.  675).  With- 
out this  deductive  quality  he  holds  that  hypothesizing  would  be 
wholly  casual  and  one  man's  theory  likely  to  be  as  good  as  another's. 


34  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY 

The  necessity  of  information  about  the  problematic  situation  is 
not  only  admitted,  but  insisted  upon.  It  expresses  precisely  the  need 
of  regulating  the  formation  of  conceptions  by  analytic  observation 
which  has  just  been  dwelt  upon.  But  it  is  denied  unqualifiedly  that 
this  information  operates  logically  after  the  manner  of  a  premise  of 
deductive  reasoning.  If  it  did,  any  two  men  with  the  same  technical 
competency  would  collect  the  same  data  and  give  their  elements  the 
same  weight.  Suggestion,  the  occurrence  of  a  hypothetical  meaning, 
is  in  last  analysis  a  brute  fact,  alogical.  It  happens  or  it  doesn't; 
a  certain  "idea"  presents  itself  or  it  doesn't;  some  other  conception 
holds  the  mind.  (That  a  similar  inductive  jump  actually  takes  place 
in  all  significant  deductions,  I  do  not  question.  But  this  does  not 
identify  their  functions,  that  is  respective  uses,  values,  characteris- 
tic results.) 

In  reference  to  the  use  of  reasoning  from  information  derived 
from  other  and  analogous  cases  Mr.  Buermeyer  seems  to  me  guilty  of 
a  fallacy  or  confusion  which  I  have  elsewhere  pointed  out.  (For 
example,  Democracy  and  Education,  p.  187.)  There  is  a  difference 
between  saying  that  the  suggestion  of  a  hypothesis  would  not  occur 
without  prior  experience  and  that  it  rests  upon  the  use  of  prior  ex- 
perience. The  former  is  a  physical  statement,  the  latter  is  a  logical 
one.  In  fact  men  often  have  a  suggestion  occur  to  them  without  being 
aware  of  the  prior  experience  which  enabled  the  suggestion  to  spring 
up.  Even  in  the  cases  when  they  are  aware  of  an  earlier  experience 
which  generated  the  suggestion  they  do  not,  if  they  are  wise, 
place  the  suggesting  experience  and  the  suggested  meaning  in  the 
relation  of  premise  and  conclusion,  but  only  in  that  of  suggester  and 
suggested — "association  of  ideas"  in  common  parlance.  The  logical 
question  is  whether  the  two  situations  are  analogous.  Knowledge 
exists  and  is  used  to  suggest  a  hypothesis.  But  the  question  for 
present  knowledge  is  whether  the  old  case  or  rule  is  or  is  not  appli- 
cable to  the  new  one.  Many  of  our  common  errors  come  from  as- 
suming that  what  is  known  in  some  cases  is  also  knowledge  for  the 
case  in  hand.  This  kind  of  subeumption  is  the  essence  of  all  dog- 
matism. Deductive  reliance  upon  old  knowledge,  that  is  putting  the 
old  case  and  the  conception  it  suggests  in  the  new  case  in  the  rela- 
tion of  logical  premise  and  conclusion,  is  precisely  the  thing  against 
which  the  inductive  function  has  to  safeguard  us.  That  a  trained 
man  can  rely  upon  old  knowledge  more  confidently  than  an  untrained 
one  is  a  fact.  But  the  logically  trained  man  still  makes  a  distinction 
between  old  knowledge  as  a  source  of  suggestions  and  as  a  deductive 
premise  for  a  conclusion.  The  analytic  inspection  upon  which  I 
have  laid  such  emphasis  as  the  crucial  thing  in  induction  has  to  ex- 


AN  ANALYSIS  OF  REFLECTIVE  THOUGHT     35 

tend  not  merely  to  the  present  problematic  situation  but  to  the  prior 
situations  from  which  a  would-be  rule  or  conclusion  springs  up. 
Only  in  this  way,  can  we  safeguard  the  acceptance  of  a  suggestion 
by  determining  the  degree  of  similiarity  which  exists  between  the  two 
cases.  Mr.  Buermeyer  refers  to  Newton's  inference  as  to  gravita- 
tion. Well,  why  not  refer  also  to  his  inference  as  to  light  ?  It  was 
the  same  man  working  with  the  same  instrumentalities.  In  one  case, 
the  supposition  of  analogy  with  prior  experiences  has  been  confirmed. 
In  the  other  case,  it  hasn't  been.  In  short,  the  hypothetical  charac- 
ter of  inductive  inference  lies  precisely  in  the  supposition  of  analogy 
between  the  present  problematic  cases  and  other  assured  cases. 
This  is  the  point  at  issue.  There  is  no  paradox  in  the  fact  that  what 
is  knowledge  in  one  context  is  hypothesis  or  even  error  in  another. 
But  it  is  a  fact  which  precludes  that  acceptance  of  prior  knowledge 
as  a  deductive  premise  upon  which  Mr.  Buermeyer 's  argument  de- 
pends. 

Upon  the  importance  in  induction  of  a  plurality  of  competing 
hypotheses  and  of  the  importance  of  elimination,  of  exclusion,  of  all 
but  one,  I  am  glad  to  find  myself  wholly  at  one  with  Mr.  Buermeyer, 
and  also  to  accept  the  explanation  which  he  gives  (on  p.  676).  I 
should  also  agree  with  Mr.  Moore  that  the  assumption  of  a  plurality 
of  hypotheses  as  applicable  (that  is,  as  worth  trying  to  apply)  to 
the  same  set  of  facts  is  of  the  essence  of  skepticism.  But  I  should 
add  two  qualifications.  Such  an  assumption  is  itself  involved  in 
the  hypotheses;  or  it  is  itself  a  hypothesis,  namely,  that  each  one 
of  a  number  of  hypotheses  having  prima  facie  claims  is  worth  de- 
veloping and  examining.  And  I  should  add  also  that  skepticism 
about  the  categorical  value  of  an  inductive  inference  is  a  prerequi- 
site of  good  thinking.  Part  of  the  worth  of  competing  hypotheses 
and  of  the  method  of  successive  elisions  is  that  it  fosters  precisely 
his  healthy  skepticism. 

But  I  can  not  see  in  acceptance  of  the  importance  of  the  method 
of  elimination  anything  which  militates  against  my  analysis.  I  can 
see  in  it  several  things  which  seem  to  go  against  Mr.  Buermeyer 's. 
For  example,  since  all  competing  hypotheses  are  equally  suggested 
by  the  problematic  situation  in  conjunction  with  prior  analogous 
situations,  they  are  not  deductive  conclusions  from  identical  premises 
but  are  suggestions  springing  up  from  different  sources.  In  the 
latter  case  each  may  need  deductive  amplification  and  be  worth 
experimental  testing.  An  assertion  that  incompatible  hypotheses  are 
deductively  grounded  in  identical  premises  is,  it  seems  to  me,  skepti- 
cism of  the  most  nihilistic  kind ;  it  destroys  the  very  possibility  of  any 
valid  deduction.  Mr.  Moore's  statement  from  this  point  of  view  is 


36  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

quite  moderate.  But  it  implies  no  depreciation  of  plurality  of  hypo- 
theses and  a  process  of  selection  among  them  by  a  method  of  elimi- 
nation. On  the  contrary.  If  one  hypothesis  is  good  because  it  starts 
one  train  of  deductive  implications  and  initiates  one  set  of  experi- 
ments, several  are  better  because  they  extend  the  operation.  In  any 
complicated  case,  it  would  be  practically  impossible  to  arrive  at  a 
sound  conclusion  save  as  various  deductive  systems  were  compared 
and  the  results  of  different  experiments  used  to  check  one  another. 

Mr.  Buermeyer's  criticism  applies  also  to  the  treatment  of  de- 
duction as  the  development  of  a  suggested  meaning  through  tracing 
its  implications,  that  is,  its  logical  connections  with  other  meanings 
or  conceptions.  His  discussion  of  this  point  is,  however,  compara- 
tively brief,  and  mine  must  also  be.  He  speaks  of  deduction  in 
modern  logic  as  "a  general  theory  of  types  of  order,  or  implica- 
tion" (p.  676).  I  see  nothing  in  this  conception  contrary  to  my  point 
of  view.  Because  ordinary  reasoning  constantly  employs  implicatory 
relationships  in  order  to  expand  or  elaborate  a  suggested  meaning, 
there  is  every  reason  why  an  abstract  theory  of  implicatory  relation- 
ships should  develop.  Many  of  those  who  have  engaged  in  the  devel- 
opment of  this  logic  would  deny  their  ultimate  instrumental  or  meth- 
odological character.  But  Mr.  Buermeyer's  general  acceptance  of 
the  instrumental  logic  does  not  suggest  any  such  disposition  on  his 
part.  He  says,  however,  that  while  the  development  of  a  content  of  a 
hypothesis  uses  these  types  of  order,  it  can  not  be  identified  with  them, 
since  it  is  partial  or  selective.  Precisely.  Just  as  induction  employs 
selected  matter-of-fact  information  in  forming  a  hypothesis,  so  de- 
duction employs  a  system  of  previously  formed  conceptions  or  mean- 
ings or  relations.  It  has  to  pick  out  and  adapt  for  the  purpose  in 
hand,  which  is  set  by  the  problem.  This  selection  is  inductive  be-4 
cause  it  involves  forming  an  hypothesis  regarding  their  value  or 
applicability  for  the  purpose  in  hand.  Their  established  position 
within  the  general  system  of  types  of  implication  does  not  guarantee 
their  appropriateness  in  the  given  context  any  more  than  the  assured 
place  of  information  in  one  context  guarantees  its  use  in  a  new 
problematic  situation. 

Up  to  this  point  I  but  repeat  my  agreement  with  Mr.  Buermeyer 
so  far  as  the  use  of  induction  in  deduction  is  concerned.  It  would 
also  be  admitted  or  claimed  that  deduction  occurs  for  the  sake  of 
experimental  testing.  More  than  this,  there  is  constant  testing  dur- 
ing the  deductive  process;  mentally  conceptions  are  tried  together 
to  see  how  they  fit  for  the  purpose  in  hand.  Otherwise,  as  Mr.  Buer- 
meyer acutely  remarks,  deduction  would  become  like  the  calculations 


AN  ANALYSIS  OF  REFLECTIVE  THOUGHT     37 

of  an  adding  machine  (p.  680 ).3  But  this  dependence  upon  and  use 
of  induction  does  not,  that  I  can  see,  affect  the  statement  that  the 
function  of  deduction,  or  deduction  logically  viewed,  consists  in 
elaboration  of  a  meaning  of  which  has  first  presented  itself  in  a 
crude,  undeveloped  form,  and  which  is  accepted  not  finally  but  as 
worth  being  made  the  base  of  development.4  In  fact,  it  is  not  easy 
to  tell  whether  or  not  Mr.  Buermeyer  denies  this  point. 

In  conclusion,  one  ultimate  point  at  issue  may  be  said  to  turn 
upon  the  relation  of  act  (or  process)  and  function,  or  as  Mr.  Buer- 
meyer points  out  the  relation  of  the  psychological  and  logical.  I 
concede  wholly  to  Mr.  Buermeyer  the  contention  that  in  the  degree  in 
which  any  job  of  thinking  is  well  done,  experimenting  and  deduc- 
tion are  involved  in  induction — and  so  on  all  the  way  around.  But 
I  deny  that  this  factual  involvement  means  logical  identification. 
This  denial  seems  to  Mr.  Buermeyer  to  imply  going  back  upon  that 
belief  in  the  intimate  relation  of  psychology  and  logic  which  is  the 
essence  of  the  pragmatic  or  instrumental  logic.  I  do  not  think  so. 
One  might  contend  that  a  science  of  physiology  depended  upon 
ability  to  detect  chemical  processes  and  trace  their  workings  with 
respect  to  all  the  functions  of  the  organism.  Would  this  cancel  the 
distinction  between  breathing  and  circulation,  even  if  it  were  shown 
that  they  not  merely  depend  upon  each  other  but  that  fundamentally 
similar  chemical  reactions  were  found  in  both?  Function  is  not  a 
separate  process:  to  suppose  that  it  is,  seems  to  me  the  error  of  all 
abstractionism  and  absolutism.  It  is,  however,  a  distinctive  matter, 
for  it  concerns  the  results  of  processes.  A  man  may  go  from  New 
York  to  Chicago  and  from  Chicago  to  New  York  upon  the  same 
tracks,  in  the  same  car  and  with  the  same  engineer.  But  the  purpose, 
the  outcome  is  different.  So  is  it  with  induction  and  deduction.  The 
more  we  become  aware  of  the  identity  of  psychological  process,  the 
more  the  difference  in  function  becomes  significant.  To  ignore  this 
distinctiveness  of  Junction  because  of  the  unity  of  act  seems  to  me 
to  deliver  the  cause  of  concrete,  psychological  thinking  into  the  hands 
of  the  enemy — those  who  assert  that  all  true  reasoning  is  deductive 

» I  take  it  that  Mr.  Buermeyer  would  probably  agree  with  me  that  the  same 
thing  holds  of  the  general  theory  of  types  of  order  or  implications  which  the 
new  school  substitutes  for  the  old  syllogism.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  they  also 
involve  induction. 

*  If  Mr.  Buermeyer  had  carried  his  criticism  to  the  point  of  stating  that 
conclusions  appear  in  every  phase  of  reflective  thinking  I  should  also  have 
agreed  with  him.  It  is  far  from  being  true  (as  a  chronological  interpretation  of 
iny  analysis  would  infer)  that  conclusion  is  postponed  till  the  problem  is  solved. 
We  accept  or  adopt  at  every  point.  The  difference  is  in  the  conditions  and 
purpose  of  the  acceptance,  as  is  suggested  above  regarding  acceptance  of  a 
hypothesis. 


38  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

and  that  induction  is  a  mere  psychological  preliminary,  important 
only  in  the  biography  of  the  individual  thinker.  I  wish  that  Mr. 
Buermeyer  would  turn  his  well-loaded  guns  upon  that  camp;  and 
in  conclusion  I  again  thank  him  for  the  opportunity  to  make  clearer 
points  which  in  How  We  Think  were  doubtless  left  in  regrettable 
obscurity. 

JOHN  DEWET. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


THE  NERVOUS  SYSTEM,  PSYCHOLOGICAL  FACT  OB 

FICTION? 

SO  habituated  have  we  become  to  the  inferior  position  which 
psychology  occupies  among  the  sciences  that  we  have  become 
accustomed  to  excuse  its  deficiencies  rather  than  to  understand  and 
correct  them.  Hence,  the  tradition  continues  that  psychology  deals 
with  vague  and  futile  materials,  not  natural  facts  which  can  be 
described  and  referred  to  valid  laws.  Indeed,  it  is  only  with  ex- 
treme reserve  that  one  grants  psychology  a  place  among  the  natural 
sciences  at  all.  Of  course  it  is  the  psychologist  himself  who  is  re- 
sponsible for  this  situation  for  he  is  only  very  slowly  prying  loose 
the  facts  of  his  domain  from  the  metaphysical  incrustations  in  which 
the  centuries  have  confined  them. 

The  psychologist 's  handling  of  the  nervous  system  is  an  excellent 
case  in  point.  The  nervous  system,  originally  brought  into  psy- 
chology as  a  means  of  concretizing  and  interpreting  the  diaphanous 
and  fleeting  states  of  mind,  has  not  yet  been  provided  with  its 
proper  place  as  a  component  factor  in  a  complex  psychological  act. 
Instead,  it  is  mainly  used  as  a  scheme  wherewith  to  handle  the 
elusive  knowings  or  awarenesses  which  are  still  all  too  prominent 
in  psychological  writings.  Although  the  nervous  system  is  made 
to  do  heavy  duty  in  psychology,  as  is  manifest  from  even  the  slight- 
est examination  of  psychological  literature,  it  is  only  in  the  case  of 
reflexes  and  similar  actions  that  it  serves  in  any  sense  as  a  descrip- 
tive factor.  In  practically  all  other  cases  the  nervous  system  is 
used  in  psychology  merely  as  an  explanatory  agent.  In  the  pres- 
ent paper  an  attempt  is  made  to  investigate  the  neural  conceptions 
prevalent  in  psychology  with  the  hope  that  we  can  thereby  suggest 
what  is  factual  and  what  fictitious  in  these  conceptions. 

Unfortunately,  at  present  it  happens  to  be  true  that  in  general, 
whether  psychologists  use  the  nervous  system  as  a  descriptive  fact 
as  in  the  study  of  reflex  action,  or  as  an  explanatory  instrument 
in  other  cases,  the  results  so  far  as  psychology  is  concerned  are 


THE  NERVOUS  SYSTEM  39 

equally  detrimental.  In  general,  we  might  say  that  two  distinct 
and  serious  disadvantages  are  thereby  sustained.  Not  only  are  the 
highly  important  nervous  functions  gravely  misinterpreted,  with 
the  consequence  that  the  whole  psychological  act  is  hopelessly  mis- 
understood, but,  what  is  probably  worse,  a  barrier  is  immediately 
set  up  preventing  future  progress  in  our  interpretation  of  psy- 
chological phenomena. 

Briefly,  let  us  examine  each  of  the  two  uses  of  the  nervous  ap- 
paratus in  psychology,  and  first  the  descriptive  use  of  it.  When  we 
describe  a  reflex  or  any  other  act  as  a  neural  apparatus  or  as  an 
effect  of  a  neural  operation  we  give  only  a  partial  description  of 
the  activity.  Either  we  make  the  nervous  apparatus  the  whole  act 
to  the  exclusion  of  the  muscular,  glandular  and  other  processes,  as 
well  as  the  stimulating  circumstances,  or  else,  when  we  include  the 
muscular,  glandular,  and  other  response  factors,  we  still  exclude 
the  stimulating  conditions  which  are  no  less  essential  factors  in 
the  whole  action.  Need  we  say  how  inaccurate  and  useless  is  the 
description  of  an  act  when  we  omit  from  it  any  factor,  whether  it 
is  muscular,  glandular  or  discriminative?  But  we  might  suggest 
how  seriously  inadequate  must  be  an  account  of  a  response  act  from 
which  is  omitted  the  specification  of  its  differential  character  and 
specific  sensitivity  to  a  particular  stimulatng  object  and  condition. 
To  omit  the  recording  of  the  stimulating  conditions  of  reflex  and 
other  psychological  reactions  means  to  seek  exclusively  in  the  re- 
action phase  of  the  behavior  for  the  mechanism  of  the  event,  which 
in  its  essence  is  an  interaction  of  a  complete  response  with  a  spe- 
cific stimulus. 

That  the  nervous  system  should  ever  have  been  made  into  the 
exclusive  materials  of  a  psychological  act  may  be  explained  by  the 
great  influence  of  histological  and  experimental  findings  upon  the 
thinking  of  psychologists.  Truly  remarkable,  of  course,  are  the 
coordinating  and  integrating  functions  of  the  nervous  apparatus 
even  when  considered  as  purely  physiological  (mechanical)  func- 
tions, but  just  as  certain  is  it  that  the  narration  of  how  allied  and 
antagonistic  reflexes  operate  as  mere  facts  of  synaptic  coordina- 
tion gives  us  a  very  slight  notion  of  the  exact  place  of  the  nervous: 
apparatus  in  a  psychological  action.  We  meet  here  with  a  para- 
dox, namely,  that  the  over-emphasis  of  the  neural  apparatus  in 
psychological  descriptions,  instead  of  adding  anything  to  our  under- 
standing of  the  nervous  system,  rather  deprives  us  of  such  an  under- 
standing, besides  inducing  us  to  place  a  very  erroneous  interpreta- 
tion upon  the  total  psychological  act.  No  one  can  gainsay  that 
experimental  work  on  the  nervous  system  is  absolutely  indispens- 


40  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

able  for  an  understanding  of  psychological  reactions,  especially  of 
the  simpler  sort,  but  to  overlook  in  such  experimentation  the  prag- 
matic neglect  of  many  other  essential  factors,  means  to  misconstrue 
the  facts  studied.  Let  us  also  remember  that  in  all  experimental 
work  the  necessity  to  use  simple  actions  in  the  laboratory  proce- 
dure results  in  an  emphasis  on  the  neural1  factors  entirely  out  of 
proportion  to  their  actual  place  in  psychological  behavior  in  general. 

Turning  now  to  the  employment  of  the  neural  apparatus  as  an 
explanatory  factor  in  psychological  interpretations,  we  find  that 
practically  always  it  serves  as  a  means  of  supporting  a  theory  of 
behavior  not  actually  derived  from  the  observation  of  such  be- 
havior. In  particular  the  neural  mechanisms  are  used  to  uphold 
some  sort  of  mentalism;  that  is  to  say,  the  neural  apparatus  is 
seized  upon  as  an  appropriate  physical  counterpart  (either  paral- 
lel, cause,  or  condition  or  result)  of  mental  states.  Among  the  con- 
ditions presumably  explained  by  the  neural  apparatus  is  the 
manner  in  which  the  "psychic,"  whether  conceived  as  stuff  or  proc- 
ess, can  operate  in  a  factual  world.  And  so  the  nervous  system  is 
taken  to  be  (1)  the  tangible  counterpart  of  the  intangible  psychic; 
or  (2)  it  serves  merely  to  fill  in  the  gaps  (subconscious  and  associa- 
tion theories)  between  the  functioning  of  mental  (awareness)  proc- 
esses; (3)  or  further,  it  is  made  to  operate  as  the  complete  substi- 
tution for  consciousness  in  cases  where  no  awareness  is  presumed 
to  be  present.  We  will  not  attempt  to  rehearse  here  all  of  the  dif- 
ficulties attendant  upon  the  confusion  of  the  nervous  system  with 
mind,  which  inevitably  results  from  employing  a  neural  explana- 
tion in  psychology.  Suffice  it  to  say  that  it  is  our  fundamental 
•conviction  that  the  necessity  to  look  upon  the  nervous  system  as  an 
-explanatory  principle  for  psychological  processes  is  for  the  most 
part  owing  to  a  lack  of  appreciation  of  the  essential  fact  of  psy- 
chological phenomena,  namely,  the  interaction  of  a  complex  organ- 
ized specific  response  with  a  specific  stimulus. 

Many  are  the  specific  ways  in  which  the  nervous  system  is  used 
in  explaining  so-called  mental  facts  or  awareness,  and  always,  we 
submit,  with  hopelessly  unsatisfactory  results.  We  take  pleasure 
in  availing  ourselves  of  Holt's  excellent  discussions2  of  the  peculiar 
interpretations  of  the  neural  functions  in  mental  activity.  In 
speaking  of  the  relation  of  automatic  or  habitual  to  so-called  con- 

i  We  doubt  much  whether  an  unbiased  judgment  would  lay  greater  stress  upon 
the  neural  factor  than  upon  the  glandular  or  muscular  phases,  although  it  seems 
clear  that  the  interrelationship  of  response  with  stimulus  would  suffer  in  any  such 
comparison. 

*  The  Concept  of  Congoioutnett,  1914,  Oh.  15.  Also  this  JOURNAL,  1915,  VoL 
XH,  pp.  365-372,  393-409. 


THE  NERVOUS  SYSTEM  41 

scious  activities  he  says,  "One  theory,  for  instance,  has  it  that  the 
cerebral  cortex  is  the  'seat  of  consciousness,'  while  habituated  un- 
conscious acts  are  done  by  the  cerebellum  and  cord.  From  which 
it  follows  that  when  a  motion  is  first  learned  (for  this  appears  to 
be  always  a  conscious  process)  it  is  learned  by  the  cerebrum,  but 
thereafter  it  is  performed  by  the  cerebellum  and  cord  (which 
never  learned  it).  A  most  plausible  conception!  And  thereafter, 
since  it  can  be  performed  either  consciously  or  unconsciously,  a 
double  set  of  nervous  mechanisms  is  maintained  in  readiness.  Or 
again,  there  is  a  view  that  'consciousness'  is  comparable  to  resist- 
ance, or  heat,  developed  at  neural  cell  or  synapse.  Unconscious- 
ness in  a  process  is  attained  when  the  neural  path  is  worn  so 
' smooth'  that  no  appreciable  heat  is  developed.  When,  then,  an 
act  has  once  become  automatic  it  can  not  be  performed  consciously, 
unless  the  organism  relearns  it  in  a  new  set  of  nerves.  This  patently 
violates  the  facts. ' ' 3  Also,  Holt  has  shown4  in  his  analysis  of  the 
drainage  theory  of  McDougall  that  sometimes  the  attempt  to  use 
the  nervous  system  as  an  explanation  of  awareness  results  in  the 
theory  that  when  the  nervous  mechanism  functions  least,  there  is 
a  maximum  of  consciousness. 

Nor  is  the  case  any  better  with  the  action  theory  of  Miinster- 
berg  which  Holt  himself  espouses,  for  there  has  never  been,  nor  can 
there  ever  be  established  any  relationship  between  the  nervous 
system  and  any  kind  of  knowing.  All  such  neural  theories  succeed 
only  in  throwing  the  nervous  system  out  of  its  perspective  in  the 
total  reaction.  No  less  has  this  been  the  case  when  the  nervous 
apparatus  is  considered  the  basis  for  the  association  of  ideas,  than 
when  the  neural  mechanism  is  assumed  to  be  a  basis  for  conscious- 
ness in  general.  Indeed,  in  Holt's  article  from  which  we  have 
quoted,  we  are  inclined  to  believe  the  spirit  of  the  discussion  is  op- 
posed to  the  conception  that  a  psychological  act  is  primarily  a 
neural  act  or  that  the  activities  involved  in  psychological  action 
are  due  to  and  can  be  explained  by  the  nervous  apparatus  involved. 
Holt's  view  when  stripped  of  its  traditional  neural  concretions  is 
not  far  from  our  hypothesis  that  psychological  behavior  consists 
of  the  stimulating  object  or  conditions  on  the  one  hand,  and  the 
action  of  the  person  on  the  other.  Indeed,  wherever  Holt  uses  an 
illustration,  his  argument  is  definitely  in  accord  with  our  own.  "We 
deem  it  most  unfortunate  that  the  neural  tradition  is  so  strong,  since 
it  induces  such  aberration  in  our  vision  of  psychological  facts  as  to 
prevent  us  from  describing  human  behavior  as  it  occurs  and  inter- 
preting it  in  factual  terms. 

3  The  Freudian  Wish,  1915,  p.  190. 
*  The  Concept  of  Consciousness,  p.  334. 


42  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

We  would  urge,  therefore,  that  psychology  should  be  emanci- 
pated from  physiology,  for  it  is  only  when  psychological  behavior 
is  studied  as  it  actually  occurs  that  justice  can  be  done  to  the 
nervous  functions  as  well  as  to  all  the  other  factors  in  psychologi- 
cal phenomena.  How  troublesome  the  neuronic  theory  is  may  be 
judged  from  the  fact  that  even  when  psychologists  consider  that 
they  are  studying  responses  to  stimuli  the  neural  prejudice  influ- 
ences them  to  consider  all  psychological  behavior  as  merely  the 
integration  of  reflexes.  Two  fundamental  objections  to  this  proce- 
dure may  be  offered.  In  the  first  place,  reflex  acts  belong  to  the 
permanent  behavior  equipment  of  the  individual  and  are  not  capable 
of  integration ; 8  and  secondly,  to  think  of  all  of  our  behavior  as 
reflexes  or  combinations  of  reflexes  means  to  overlook  the  great 
variety  and  complexity  of  our  actual  behavior.  Especially  can 
such  a  conception  not  do  justice  in  any  sense  to  the  complex  social, 
esthetic,  and  moral  adaptations  to  our  human  surroundings.  We 
wonder  if  anyone  ever  seriously  considered  the  nervous  system  as 
such  to  be  of  any  service  in  distinguishing  between  two  objects, 
to  say  nothing  of  a  difference  between  the  alternatives  of  a  moral 
issue.  But  it  is  implied  that  in  simpler  cases  the  nervous  system 
does  perform  such  functions.  Thus,  the  supporters  of  the  neuronic 
theory  necessarily  overlook  the  presence  in  the  behavior  equipment 
of  the  person  of  other  very  important  types  of  acts  besides  re- 
flexes, as  well  as  all  the  other  specific  facts  of  human  adaptation 
other  than  neural  action.  To  deny  then,  that  all  of  our  behavior 
is  reflex  in  form  does  not  mean  in  any  sense  to  neglect  or  deny  any 
quality  or  value  of  reflexes,  but  merely  not  to  ascribe  to  them  quali- 
ties they  do  not  have,  nor  attribute  to  them  vague  and  mystic  prop- 
erties of  becoming  something  else  by  concretion  and  aggregation. 
For  it  is  inevitable  when  we  make  reflexes  the  basis  of  every  re- 
action that  we  introduce  surreptitiously  and  ad  hoc  qualities  and 
conditions  which  really  are  not  there.  An  excellent  example  of 
this  (because  in  this  matter  psychologists  follow  the  physiologists) 
is  the  case  of  the  physiologists  who  assume  that  upon  the  series  of 
physiological  facts  which  they  study  there  is  crudely  superimposed 
another  series  which  they  call  psychic. 

The  neuronic  theory,  we  submit,  stands  in  the  way  of  psychol- 
ogists who  would  develop  a  concrete  science  of  actual  human  be- 
havior, for  such  behavior,  it  need  hardly  be  argued,  is  essentially 
such  a  comjlex  adaptation  to  conditions  that  it  is  unthinkable  that 
a  neural  theory  could  be  an  explanation  of  it.  Moreover,  to  cling 

•  In  the  psychological  process  of  integration  we  assume  that  acta  lose  their 
identification  in  becoming  parts  of  larger  acts. 


THE  NERVOUS  SYSTEM  43 

to  such  a  theory  means  to  make  the  reflex  act  the  prototype  of 
human  action.  And  just  here  is  where  the  extreme  deficiency  of 
the  neural  theory  appears,  for  by  retaining  it  as  a  general  means 
of  explanation  we  overlook  its  actual  function  and  value  as  a  com- 
ponent in  all  psychological  phenomena. 

If,  while  ourselves  rejecting  neural  explanations  of  psycho- 
logical action,  we  still  seek  a  justification  for  the  belief  in  such 
reputed  explanations,  we  can  find  it  in  the  overpowering  impulse 
to  make  a  rigid  and  fixed  explanation  of  such  utterly  important 
and  exceedingly  difficult  facts  as  psychological  phenomena  are. 
How  vain  is  such  a  quest  is  clear  from  the  fact  that  quite  aside 
from  its  violation  of  scientific  methodology  (namely,  to  seek  the 
cause  of  a  phenomenon  in  a  part  of  itself)  we  maintain,  and  with 
perfect  safety  we  believe,  that  a  genuinely  critical  search  will 
reveal  not  a  single  valid  principle  of  explanation  which  psychology 
has  derived  from  physiology — although  this  does  not  deny,  in  any 
sense,  that  many  valuable  psychological  principles  were  worked 
out  by  physiologists.  In  order  not  to  be  misunderstood  at 
this  point  let  us  forthwith  distinguish  between  the  useful,  nay, 
necessary  employment  of  the  neural  factors  as  descriptive  elements 
of  actual  reaction  systems  from  the  useless  and  pernicious  employ- 
ment of  the  neural  apparatus  as  an  explanatory  process.  We  pro- 
pose with  all  emphasis  to  distinguish  between  (1)  the  description 
of  the  exceedingly  important  part  which  the  synaptic  coordination 
processes  as  integrative  functions  play  in  every  reaction  system,6 
and  (2)  the  neural  structures  and  functions  which  are  implied  to 
exist  beside  the  psychological  response  and  to  explain  it.  In  plainer 
words,  let  us  distinguish  between  the  facts  which  the  neurologist 
and  nerve  physiologist  have  discovered  and  verified  and  the  neural 
theories  which  the  older  psychologists  have  invented  to  materialize 
their  psychism.  Let  it  not  be  overlooked  that  we  do  not  deny  that 
in  many  cases  the  psychologists '  imaginary  neurology  is  based  upon 
a  germ  of  fact.  A  case  in  point  is  the  elaboration  of  the  neurologi- 
cal fact  that  the  impulse  meets  with  greater  resistance  at  the 
synapse  than  in  a  nerve  trunk,  into  the  fiction  that  synaptic  re- 
sistance is  the  cause  or  condition  of  such  complex  action  as  remem- 
bering or  knowing.  Such  inventions  consist  primarily,  of  course, 
in  the  translation  of  associationistic  mechanisms  into  neural  terms. 

It  is  all  very  well  to  desire  fixed  materials  of  references  with 
which  to  secure  complex  phenomena,  but  as  a  matter  of  fact  the 
nervous  apparatus  can  not  accomplish  any  such  purpose,  and  pri- 

8  Cf.  our  discussion  of  the  reaction  system  in  this  JOURNAL,  1921,  Vol.  XVIII, 
p.  263. 


44  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

marily,  of  course,  because  there  does  not  eiist  any  need  to  anchor 
down  psychological  facts  when  we  consider  such  facts  to  be  con- 
crete responses  to  stimuli,  as  indeed  they  are.  We  cheerfully  ad- 
mit, as  we  have  previously  observed,  that  for  extreme  mentalists 
or  spiritualists  the  neural  mechanisms  do  serve  as  stable  supports, 
but  who,  we  might  ask,  would  be  willing  to  accept  a  type  of  psy- 
chology needing  such  support? 

To  test  our  proposition  concerning  the  negative  value  of  neural 
mechanisms  in  the  interpretation  of  behavior  we  might  consider 
the  case  of  the  child  learning  to  keep  his  finger  away  from  the 
burning  candle.  In  particular,  we  might  study  Holt's  neural  inter- 
pretation, since  this  is  one  of  the  most  recently  formulated  views 
based  upon  a  mercilessly  severe  criticism  of  other  neural  explana- 
tions. After  rejecting  the  Meynert  scheme  which  James  has  made 
into  a  classic,  Holt  assumes  that  the  child  is  endowed  with  two  re- 
flexes, one  for  extension  and  the  other  for  retraction.  Now  the 
explanation  consists  in  positing  a  greater  "openness"  and  "wear- 
ing down"  of  the  second  or  retractive  path  so  that  it  will  operate 
in  preference  to  the  first.  But  even  if  we  agree  to  overlook  en- 
tirely the  absolutely  hypothetical  character  of  the  "openness"  and 
"wearing  down"  of  paths,  must  we  not  assume,  if  the  two  reflexes 
are  present,  that  both  pathways  are  already  open  and  worn  down! 
Yet  Holt  finds  it  necessary  to  explain  how  the  second  or  retraction 
path  is  opened  and  worn  down  relatively  more.  This  explanation 
which  he  offers  is  twofold.  In  the  first  place,  he  asserts  that  the 
prolonged  pain  which  the  child  suffers  continues  the  retraction 
stimulus  for  a  long  period,  thus  causing  the  path  to  wear  down. 
And  in  the  second  place,  he  suggests  that  just  as  the  first  five 
pedestrians  across  a  snow-covered  field  do  more  than  the  next 
twenty-five  toward  making  a  path,  so  the  passage  of  a  first  nervous 
impulse  over  a  path  of  high  resistance  wears  it  down  more  than 
the  same  impulse  would  wear  an  already  opened  tract.7 

As  to  the  first  point,  what  does  Holt  mean  by  pain  t  Not  a  men- 
tal something,  let  us  hope.  For  if  he  does,  he  not  only  abjures  the 
necessity  for  explaining  anything,  since  by  admitting  mentalities  he 
need  merely  associate  with  pain  an  "idea  of  retraction"  as  in  the 
original  Meynert  scheme,  but  he  also  involves  himself  in  the  far 
worse  situation  that  he  can  never  demonstrate  the  connection  be- 
tween such  a  mental  state  and  a  nervous  mechanism,  to  say  nothing 
at  all  of  how  such  a  mental  state  can  wear  down  a  neural  path.  On 
the  other  hand,  if  he  means  a  pain  reaction,  that  is  to  say,  a  response 
in  which  the  person  discriminates  pain,  then  the  pain  reaction  clearly 

T  The  Freudian  With,  p.  69. 


THE  NERVOUS  SYSTEM  45 

can  be  a  stimulus  to  the  child  to  learn  to  withdraw  his  hand  from 
the  candle  flame.  But  in  this  case,  of  course,  the  learning  consists 
of  the  acquisition  of  a  complete  reaction  system  and  not  the  wearing 
down  of  a  path  in  the  nervous  system. 

And  now  let  us  examine  the  second  part,  namely,  that  the  retrac- 
tion path  is  worn  down  more  because  it  is  a  new  path.  Here  again 
it  is  difficult  to  see  why  the  retraction  path  is  new,  since  Holt  assumes 
the  two  reflexes  to  be  present.  And  as  to  establishing  a  balance 
between  the  two,8  in  what  sense  is  that  learning  to  keep  the  finger 
out  of  the  flame  when  in  fact  the  balance  means  merely  that  both 
acts  will  be  performed.  That  is  to  say,  each  time  the  child  puts  his 
finger  into  the  flame  he  will  also  withdraw  it.  No,  Holt  must  cleave 
to  the  notion  of  a  greater  openness  of  the  second  path,  and  not 
merely  a  balance  between  the  two,  but,  even  if  we  allow  that  the 
retraction  path  is  new  and  that  a  new  path  is  opened  more  at  first, 
how  is  Holt's  problem  any  nearer  a  solution?  What  more  can  hap- 
pen with  the  retraction  path  than  that  it  reaches  the  condition  of 
the  extension  path  when  the  latter  first  began  to  be  used. 

To  us  the  entire  explanation  is  exceedingly  fantastic,  and  for  the 
reason,  we  might  suggest,  that  Holt  is  attempting  to  make  the  entire 
learning  a  neural  affair,9  even  to  making  the  stimulating  situation 
(the  pain  reaction)  a  factor  in  the  neural  process.  Were  it  not  for 
the  faith  in  the  neural  theory  as  an  explanatory  mechanism  it  is 
doubtful  whether  both  reactions  would  have  been  considered  reflexes 
at  all.  Now  if  we  are  correct  in  assuming  that  Holt's  handling  of 
the  neural  theory  is  as  effective  as  any,  then  we  mean  to  suggest  the 
possible  incapacity  of  any  of  them  to  account  for  psychological  facts. 

Very  differently  is  the  learning  explained  on  the  organismic- 
response10  and  stimulus  basis.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  although  it  makes 
little  difference  for  the  explanation,  we  need  not  consider  the  first  or 
extension  act  as  a  reflex.  Be  that  as  it  may,  we  consider  the  act  to  be 
present  and  because  the  result  is  disastrous  or  unsatisfactory  (pain- 
ful) we  observe  a  new  act  to  be  built  up.  We  assume  that  the  with- 
drawing action  constitutes  a  new  response  built  up  for  adaptation 
to  the  candle  as  a  consequence  of  the  previous  reaction  to  that  candle 
and  in  addition  to  the  retraction  reflex.  In  other  words,  there  is 
a  new  behavior  segment  established  in  which  the  candle  constitutes 
the  stimulus.  It  is  the  acquisition  of  this  reaction  system  which 
constitutes  the  learning. 

s  Il>id.,  p.  72. 

•  At  this  point  'he  is  not  living  up  to  his  promise  in  the  criticism  of  neural 
theories. 

10  The  term  organismic  is  used  to  point  out  the  absolute  inseparability  of  the 
stimulus  and  response  factors  in  a  psychological  action. 


46  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

We  assume  that  in  the  second  or  new  behavior  segment,  the  child 
discriminates  the  stimulus  differently  or  has  developed  a  new  mean- 
ing for  the  candle  flame,  a  new  meaning  in  the  sense  that  a  new  dif- 
ferential response  is  called  out  by  it.  This  is  the  essential  fact  in  all 
perceptual  activities.  Instead  of  perceiving  the  object  as  something 
to  touch,  it  is  now  something  that  hurts  and  must  be  (is)  left  alone. 
The  essentially  perceptual  phase  of  the  new  behavior  segment  is  a 
vestigial  or  incipient  performance  of  the  previous  reaction,  which 
precedes  a  final  overt  response — the  withdrawal  of  the  hand  or  some 
other  mode  of  action.  Especially  must  we  guard  here  against  any 
implication  that  the  candle  flame  in  the  second  behavior  segment 
calls  out  an  "idea"  of  the  burn  as  in  the  Meynert- James  scheme. 
No  such  factitious  element  is  in  any  sense  involved  in  our  exposition. 
The  strictly  perceptual  phase  of  the  behavior  segment  is  an  act  of 
the  person  in  precisely  the  exact  form  as  in  the  first  instance.  More- 
over, the  perceptual  act  is  not  in  any  sense  merely  a  neural  mechan- 
ism but  a  complete  behavior,  although  it  is  true  enough  that  it  is  not 
as  open  to  the  spectator's  observation  as  the  first  act.  Also  we  must 
observe  that  in  the  candle-flame  situation  the  perceptual  act  happens 
to  be  a  visual  response ;  that  isi  to  say,  a  reaction  system  in  which  the 
primary  receptor  is  ocular,  although  the  complete  reaction  system 
does  involve  in  addition  tactual  factors.  The  new  retraction  act, 
then,  is  one  in  which  the  child's  contact  with  the  candle  is  visual. 
In  fact  the  importance  of  the  new  acquisition  lies  precisely  in  the 
avoidance  of  any  actual  touching  of  the  object.  But  notice,  however, 
that  the  learning  may  be  just  as  effective  if  the  new  act  involves 
auditory  or  olfactory  perception.  And  finally,  we  must  be  very  care- 
ful not  to  confuse  the  anticipatory  perceptual  reaction  system  with 
the  final  withdrawal  or  other  response  which  follows  closely  upon 
the  operation  of  the  former. 

The  importance  and  value  of  our  hypothesis  as  compared  with 
any  neural  one,  of  which  we  take  Holt's  to  be  an  especially  good 
example,  is  further  indicated  in  the  fact  that  it  can  accomplish  two 
things  which  Holt  admits  his  theory  can  not,11  namely,  (1)  account 
for  all  kinds  of  learning  and  (2)  explain  the  child's  concept  of 
candle.  As  to  the  first,  or  the  explanation  of  other  kinds  of  learn- 
ing, from  our  standpoint  all  learning,  whether  manual  (handicraft), 
technical  (skill,  industrial  or  esthetic),  or  informational  (book  learn- 
ing) consists  of  the  organization  of  new  behavior  segments,  that  is, 
specific  responses  to  specific  stimulating  objects  or  conditions.  Each 
response  constitutes  the  acquisition  of  a  new  specific  adaptation  to 

11  The  Freudian  Wish,  p.  74. 


THE  NERVOUS  SYSTEM  47 

particular  surrounding  objects.  It  is  thus  that  capacities  and  in- 
formation are  acquired  by  the  person. 

Concepts,  from  our  standpoint  are  completely  implicit  or  vestig- 
ial responses  to  surrounding  objects.  In  other  words,  they  are  the 
ordinary  perceptual  responses  so  abstracted  from  the  original  con- 
tact with  things  through  the  removal  of  the  stimulating  object,  that 
they  are  aroused  to  action  through  a  substitution  stimulus.12  Very 
simply  explained,  then,  are  the  child's  concepts  of  the  candle;  they 
are  merely  residual  responses  left  over  from  the  original  contacts 
with  the  candle,  and  which  can  be  translated  into  verbal  terms.  That 
concepts  are  derived  from  originally  overt  contacts  with  objects  no 
one  will  deny,  for  it  is  a  matter  of  course  that  the  number  and  variety 
of  our  concepts  depend  upon  our  actual  past  experiences.  Also,  the 
degree  of  abstraction  of  our  concepts  depends  upon  whether  our 
original  contacts  with  the  conceived  objects  were  direct  (actual)  or 
indirect  (imparted  to  us  through  speech  or  printed  matter).  Once 
more,  unless  concepts  were  implicit  actions  derived  from  our  actual 
previous  contacts  with  our  stimulating  objects,  how  could  it  ever  be 
possible  to  react  to  these  objects  in  their  absence?  To  repeat,  our 
concepts  of  objects  are  the  reaction  systems  developed  to  those 
things,  which  can  function  relatively  independently  of  them.13 

Some  there  are  who  will  still  persist  in  the  criticism  that  after 
all  the  organism ic  hypothesis  affords  us  no  intimation  as  to  why 
reaction  systems  are  built  up  as  responses  to  stimulation  objects. 
In  considering  this  criticism  two  points  must  be  carefully  distin- 
guished, one  of  which  has  no  answer.  If  one  means  by  this  criti- 
cism that  we  have  not  specified  why  it  is  that  any  empirically  spe- 
cific response  is  developed  to  a  particular  stimulus,  we  might  answer 
that  in  our  argument  we  assumed  that  any  given  stimulating  situa- 
tion would  necessarily  call  out  an  adaptive  reaction  correlated  with 
that  situation;  since,  further,  we  fundamentally  assume  that  psy- 
chological reactions  are  phenomena  of  adaptation.  But  observe 
that  the  stimulating  situations  are  not  the  exclusive  conditions  for 
the  building  up  of  particular  reactions.  Another  very  important 
set  of  conditions  is  found  in  the  previous  psychological  development 
of  the  organism,  and  a  by  no  means  negligible  circumstance  is  the 
biological  organization  of  the  individual.  Nor  do  all  of  these  in 
their  aggregate  exhaust  the  conditions  for  the  acquisition  of  reac- 
tion systems;  there  are  many  others  if  only  we  devote  ourselves  to 
a  study  of  psychological  phenomena  under  the  factual  conditions 
of  their  development  and  occurrence.  Most  fortunate  the  day  when 

«  Cf.  Kantor,  "  An  Objective  Interpretation  of  Meanings,"  Am.  Jour.  Pty., 
1921,  Vol.  XXXn,  pp.  231  sq. 

is  Through  substitution  of  stimuli,  as  we  have  said  above. 


48  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

psychologists  will  give  up  the  ideas  that  psychological  phenomena 
are  simple  or  that  they  can  be  reduced  to  such  partial  explanatory 
terms  as  are  involved  in  the  nervous  mechanism.  Observe,  how- 
ever, that  whatever  explanation  there  be  for  the  acquisition  of  our 
particular  reactions,  it  can  not  exist  otherwise  than  in  the  study  of 
concrete  behavior  segments. 

On  the  other  hand,  if  one  takes  the  import  of  the  criticism  we 
have  mentioned  to  be  that  we  do  not  know  how  reaction  systems 
are  built  up  at  all,  we  can  only  question  the  legitimacy  of  the  ques- 
tion. We  take  it  that  we  are  no  more  obliged  to  explain  why  psy- 
chological organisms  have  their  specific  properties  (for  we  may 
assume  the  fact  of  building  up  reaction  systems  as  a  quality  of  the 
organism)  than  the  physicist  is  required  to  explain  why  bodies  fall. 
Not  that  we  would  restrict  any  speculation  based  upon  fact  and 
the  criteria  of  logic,  but  we  do  insist  that  whatever  we  believe  and 
assert  concerning  psychological  phenomena  must  be  in  accord  with 
observable  fact  and  in  harmony  with  the  logic  of  science.  In  point 
of  fact,  is  it  not  obvious  that  the  criticism  just  discussed  is  urged 
entirely  in  the  interest  of  a  neural  explanation,  which  we  of  course 
take  to  be  something  different  from  a  psychological  description  T 

Next  to  the  misinterpretation  of  the  entire  reaction,  by  far  the 
greatest  damage  sustained  by  psychology  from  the  neuronic  theory 
is  the  retardation  in  the  understanding  of  the  actual  function  of 
the  neural  factors  of  reaction  systems.  If  it  is  true,  as  we  be- 
lieve, that  in  much  of  current  psychological  work  an  erroneous 
use  of  the  nervous  apparatus  is  made,  then  it  appears  plausible 
that  we  are  not  acquiring  all  the  information  we  should  concern- 
ing the  actual  operation  of  that  important  component  of  all  re- 
actions. Surprisingly  little  is  yet  known  of  the  exact  workings  of 
the  neural  mechanisms,  and  since  numerous  are  the  facts  to  be 
known  it  therefore  behooves  us  to  let  no  false  hypothesis  prevent 
us  from  investigating  neural  mechanisms  as  actual  phases  of  be- 
havior, that  is  to  say  as  exceedingly  complex  coordinating  systems, 
and  not  as  causes  of  acts  or  counterparts  of  invented  mentalities. 

Not  untrue  is  it  to  say,  then,  that  the  organismic  hypothesis  is 
presented  in  the  interest  of  an  emended  conception  of  the  relation- 
ship between  psychology  and  biology.  Instead  of  considering  bio- 
logical phenomena  as  merely  explanatory  schemes  for  psychology,14 
we  must  study  the  physiological  facts  with  which  psychology  is 
concerned  as  actual  and  essential  components  of  a  larger  adapta- 
tion process,  namely,  the  psychological  response.  No  latitude  is 

"The  reader  will  recall  that  among  the  first  achievements  of  "  biological 
psychology  ' '  was  the  redefinition  of  ' '  consciousness  "  as  a  thing  or  process  de- 
veloped to  maintain  the  life  of  animals. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  49 

allowed  us  in  this  matter  at  all,  and  we  dare  not  omit  any  physio- 
logical fact,  because  it  is  just  a  fact  of  nature  that  all  psychologi- 
cal organisms  are  biological  organisms  also.  This  truth,  of  course, 
should  offer  no  inducement  to  the  psychologist  to  use  physiological 
facts  or  fables  to  explain  the  phenomena  of  his  scientific  domain. 
Nor  is  this  evil  necessary  in  any  sense  when  we  study  psychological 
responses  as  definite  autonomous  events  existing  in  nature.  Of 
course,  if  we  consider  the  phenomena  of  psychology  to  be  correlates 
or  adjuncts  of  physiological  facts  we  must  frequently  resort  to  the 
magical  use  of  the  nervous  system.  But  regardless  of  how  easily 
the  words  cortical  and  cerebral  roll  from  the  tongue  of  the  psychol- 
ogist when  he  wishes  to  explain  some  mentalistic  fact,15  the  neurol- 
ogist still  can  not  find  in  the  cortex  any  of  the  magical  conveni- 
ences which  the  psychologist  requires.16  For  example,  there  has 
never  been  any  neural  machinery  discovered  to  account  either  for 
the  existence  or  the  association  of  mentalistic  ideas.17 

Finally,  we  must  not  be  misled  by  the  overlapping  of  some  of 
the  psychological  data  with  biological  facts  into  distorting  such  data 
by  the  indulgence  in  general  physiological  explanations;  for  in 
the  first  place,  psychological  phenomena  are  no  more  physiological 
than  they  are  physical,  and  in  the  second  place,  the  argument  that 
psychology  is  based  on  physiology  is  no  more  valid  than  the  argu- 
ment that  all  sciences,  because  they  are  human  phenomena,  are 
based  upon  sociology.  The  only  valid  scientific  procedure  is  to 
accord  full  recognition  to  any  facts  that  we  study  without  attempt- 
ing violently  to  transform  them  into  something  else. 

J.  E.  KANTOB. 
INDIANA  UNIVERSITY. 

BOOK  REVIEWS 

Christianisme  et  Neo-Platonisme  dans  la  Formation  de  Saint  Angus- 
tin.    CHARLES  BOYER.    Paris :  Gabriel  Beauchesne.    1921. 

L'Idee  de  Verite  dans  la  Philosophic  de  Saint  Augustin.    CHARLES 
BOYER.    Paris :  Gabriel  Beauchesne.    1921.    Pp.  233. 
We  have  bracketed  these  two  treatises,  not  merely  because  they 

15  An  explanation  that  frequently  takes  the  form  of  thin  king  that  specific 
brain  cells  are  connected  in  some  way  with  particular  thoughts. 

i«In  similar  fashion  when  the  physiologist  hits  upon  some  fact  which  th« 
mere  study  of  neural  mechanism  does  not  and  can  not  explain  he  utters  the  magic 
word  ' '  consciousness. ' ' 

if  Cf.  Herriek,  Introduction  to  Neurology,  1920,  Ch.  20.  While  we  can  not 
accept  in  the  slightest  Bergson  's  metaphysical  substitution  for  the  neuronic  theory 
(cf.  Matter  and  Memory)  we  must  nevertheless  commend  his  excellent  exposure  of 
the  defects  of  that  theory. 


50  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

are  the  work  of  the  same  author,  but  because  they  bear  upon  two 
distinct  phases  of  a  very  large  theme  and  serve  admirably  to  deepen 
our  appreciation  of  one  of  the  most  notable  and  dominating  char- 
acters in  the  early  development  of  western  European  thought.  The 
modern  world,  or  that  portion  of  it,  at  least,  which  takes  little  im- 
mediate interest  in  the  successive  philosophic  positions  of  Latin 
Christianity,  has  drifted  a  long  way  from  St.  Augustine  and  the 
speculations  that  made  him  so  commanding  a  figure  in  the  course  of 
the  centuries  even  among  thinkers  who  have  had  no  obvious  concern 
with  theology.  Scholars  like  Picavet,  or  Harnack,  or  Loofs,  may  call 
attention  to  particular  phases  of  his  genius,  and  a  group  of  students 
here  and  there  may  read  and  note,  but,  on  the  whole,  interest  in 
his  writings  has  flagged,  and  he  remains  for  the  philosophic  world  at 
large,  even  in  centers  that  are  supposed  to  cultivate  a  tradition  of 
familiarity  with  his  views,  one  of  that  great  brotherhood  of  authors 
who  are  more  written  about  than  read.  Yet  he  is  as  actual  and  com- 
pelling in  his  wistful  outlook  on  the  mystery  of  things  as  Plato  or 
Aristotle,  and  more  modern,  if  less  didactic,  than  Thomas  of  Aquin 
himself. 

M.  Boyer,  one  may  be  sure,  is  persuaded  of  all  this;  yet  his 
first  treatise,  in  spite  of  many  an  apparent  statement  to  the  contrary, 
limits  the  scope  of  his  essays  to  two  distinct  points  which  he  develops 
with  a  precision  and  an  economy  of  argument  that  is  as  scientific 
as  it  is  conciliating  and  restrained  in  tone  from  first  to  last.  In  the 
earlier  volume  he  traces  the  story  of  the  retreat  at  Cassisiacum,  and 
maintains,  against  Boissier,  Harnack  and  Loofs,  and  notably  against 
Thimmes,  to  name  only  the  more  distinguished  scholars  with  whom 
he  takes  issue  on  this  point,  that  it  was  to  Catholic  Christianity,  and 
not  to  Neo-Platonism,  that  the  mind  of  Augustine  yielded  itself 
in  the  famous  garden  scene  that  took  place  at  Milan  in  the  month 
of  September,  386.  The  succeeding  nine  years  were  years  of  develop- 
ment; but  they  were  years  of  orientation,  too;  for  they  were  the 
years  of  a  neophyte  who  felt— perhaps  too  confidently — that  he  had 
discovered  in  the  Neo-Platonic  School  a  rational  support  for  the 
change  in  his  mental  outlook  that  his  "conversion"  had  inevitably 
forced  upon  him.  The  Confessions  that  all  the  world  knows  and 
the  Dialogues,  a  purely  philosophical  work  of  absorbing  interest 
and  great  beauty,  in  spite  of  the  note  of  youth  that  pulses  through 
it,  furnish  the  ground  of  this  contention.  They  simply  will  not 
bear  the  interpretation  that  the  critics  mentioned  above  have  put 
upon  them;  and  M.  Boyer 's  pages  literally  bristle  with  subsidiary 
fact  and  text  in  corroboration  of  this  more  reasonable  conclusion. 

In  the  subsequent  work,  L'Idee  de  Verite  dams  la  Philosophic 


BOOK  REVIEWS  51 

i 

de  Saint  Augustin,  published  soon  after  La  Formation,  M.  Boyer 
touches  upon  matter  that  is  more  actual  to  the  present-day  student 
of  philosophy.  Realist,  Conceptualist,  Pragmatist,  Bergsonian,  or 
Neo-Scholastic,  each  one  of  us  has  his  metaphysic — some  of  us, 
perhaps,  a  meta-metaphysic — on  the  meaning  of  Truth;  and  not  a 
little  depends  on  the  texture  of  mind  with  which  he  approaches  the 
problem. 

In  the  years  before  the  War  there  was  a  good  deal  of  discussion 
on  the  subject,  hardly  any  of  it  thorough,  or  profound,  unless  we 
except  Mr.  H.  H.  Joachim's  really  able  essay.  If  the  general  move- 
ment of  ideas  has  since  set  in  other  directions,  M.  Boyer 's  study 
will  not  on  that  account  suffer  from  a  lack  of  timeliness ;  for  there 
is  something,  not  merely  fundamental,  but  ineluctable  and  far-reach- 
ing, in  the  answers  that  one  gives  to  these  questions  in  limine.  One's 
mental  states,  the  quality  of  one's  assents,  one's  ultimate  infer- 
ences,— these  things  are  involved  in  them  from  the  start.  All  this 
was  felt  as  acutely  in  St.  Augustine's  day  as  in  our  own.  The  pre- 
vailing skepticism  borrowed  a  certain  tone  and  eclat  from  the 
brilliant  thinkers  against  whom  the  contra  Academicos  libri  ires 
were  directed  from  the  villa  at  Cassisiacum.  Truth,  after  all,  was 
a  discoverable  thing;  and  the  great  neophyte  was  determined  to 
bring  that  assurance  home  to  the  inquirers  of  his  time.  Reducendi 
mihi  videntur  homines  .  .  .  in  spem  reperiendae  veritatis,  he  wrote 
in  386.  It  was  an  ambition  in  every  way  worthy  of  so  tireless  and 
high-souled  a  thinker. 

M.  Boyer  sketches  for  us  in  lucid  outline  the  general  drift  of 
the  argument  by  which  this  life-purpose  was  carried  out.  He  distin- 
guishes four  different  senses  in  which  the  word  truth  is  employed  by 
Augustine  throughout  his  writings.  There  is,  first  of  all,  the  com- 
mon, or  logical,  sense  which  pervades  all  the  more  recondite  uses  of 
the  term,  and  which,  in  a  sense,  may  be  said  to  inspire  them.  It  is 
the  assertion  or  affirmation,  of  that  which  is,  the  identification, 
namely,  of  reality  with  whatever  may  be  affirmed  of  it.  From  this 
logical  sense  of  the  term  the  transition  to  its  more  metaphysical  sup- 
positions may  be  inferred.  There  are  three  of  these:  (a)  the  adequa- 
tional  sense,  as  embodied  in  the  relation  between  the  thing  and  the 
idea;  (£)  the  Logos,  or  filiative,  sense,  known  only  through  the 
Christian  revelation,  in  virtue  of  which  the  Son  is  the  unique  and 
perfect  Expression  of  the  Father;  and  (y)  finally,  the  graduate 
sense,  which  is  to  be  found  only  in  finite,  or  derived  Reality,  and 
which  is  rooted  in  the  measure,  or  grade,  of  being  that  things  have 
as  imaging  in  their  several  likenesses,  or  adumbrations,  the  primary 
reality  which  gives  them  their  measure  of  truth.  It  is  in  this  sense 


52  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

that  the  Scholastics,  later  on,  maintain  with  Aquinas  that  things  are 
true  in  proportion  to  their  being;  maxime  vera  sunt  maxime  entia. 
That  St.  Augustine  in  his  various  expositions  of  this  aspect  of  the 
truth  of  things  laid  himself  open  to  grave  misapprehension  in  after 
times,  many  a  chapter  in  the  Summa  contra  Gentiles,  to  say  nothing 
of  the  various  Schools  of  Ontologism  in  the  last  century,  abundantly 
proves.  M.  Beyer,  though  but  a  modest  beginner,  is  to  be  con- 
gratulated on  this  really  dignified  and  scholarly  piece  of  work. 

C.  C.  CLIFFORD. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

Dieu — Son  Existence  et  sa  Nature.  F.  R.  GARRIGOU-LAORANGE,  des 
Freres  Precheurs.  Paris:  Gabriel  Beauchesne.  1915.  Pp.  770.1 
Let  us  say  frankly  at  the  outset  that  the  delay  in  noticing  this 
work  of  the  distinguished  Thomist  and  Professor  at  the  Angelical, 
whose  name  is  not  as  well  known  to  American  students  of  philosophy 
as  it  ought  to  be,  is  out  of  all  proportion  to  its  merits  which  are  many 
and  satisfying  to  a  marked  degree.  The  author  describes  his  book, 
in  a  challenging  sub-title,  as  a  Solution  Thomiste  des  Antinomies 
Agnostiques.  Whether  the  class  of  students  to  whom  we  venture  to 
recommend  it  for  consultation,  if  not  for  exhaustive  reading,  will 
agree  with  this  initial  claim  will  depend,  of  course,  on  his  previous 
equipment  and  his  general  attitude  towards  the  more  fundamental 
problems  of  epistemology.  The  work,  in  spite  of  its  bulk,  is  pro- 
fessedly a  text-book,  with  a  text-book's  inevitable  limitations;  but  it 
will  be  found  to  be  a  very  stimulating  and  wholesome  contribution 
to  many  a  more  pretentious  effort  notwithstanding  that  fact.  On 
not  a  few  of  the  problems  that  the  late  Professor  William  James 
tried  to  illuminate  in  his  own  inimitable  and  engaging  way,  F. 
Garrigou-Lagrange  speaks  with  compelling  attention,  and,  be  it  add- 
ed, with  a  courage  as  refreshing  as  that  of  the  great  Harvard  teacher 
himself.  As  might  be  expected,  the  range  of  subjects  touched  upon 
in  the  course  of  the  work  is  almost  as  extensive  as  the  history  of  west- 
ern thought  itself;  but  the  subjects  themselves  are  pressing,  actual 
and  modern, — as  the  array  of  foot-notes  and  long  citations,  embodied 
candidly  in  the  text,  makes  clear.  Perhaps  the  chief  merits  of  the 
book  are  its  downright  attitude  towards  those  Kantian  strictures  on 
causality  which  so  obsess  the  modern  student  of  thought,  and  its  ob- 
vious acquaintance  with  the  philosophic  literature  of  our  time. 

C.  C.  CLIFFORD. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

1  The  book  is  now  in  its  third  edition. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  53 

Values,  Immediate  and  Contributory.    MAURICE  PICARD.     The  New 

York  University  Press.    1920.    Pp.  vi  +  197. 

While  primarily  concerned  with  maintaining  certain  theses  on 
specific  and  technical  points  of  value  theory,  this  little  book  has  a 
much  wider  appeal.  It  is  at  once  too  limited  in  scope  and  technical 
in  treatment  to  afford  the  general  introduction  the  present  state  of 
the  subject  makes  so  desirable,  but  it  formulates  and  discusses  some 
of  the  chief  problems  which  such  a  book  must  take  into  account. 
Part  I.  deals  acutely  and  lucidly  with  questions  of  analysis,  origin 
and  interrelation  of  values.  Part  II.,  perhaps  somewhat  less  suc- 
cessfully, with  the  normative  aspects  of  the  problem.  Mr.  Picard 
takes  a  definite  standpoint.  He  describes  himself  as  a  Pragmatist 
with  certain  reservations.  But  this  prevents  him  neither  from  tak- 
ing seriously,  nor  from  understanding — up  to  a  point — the  philos- 
ophy of  absolute  values  which  he  is  called  upon  to  criticize. 

Mr.  Picard  sets  himself  the  task  of  settling  a  dispute  which  has 
long  occupied  students  of  value  theory,  namely  the  relation  of  in- 
trinsic and  instrumental,  or  of  immediate  and  contributory  values 
to  each  other.  "My  whole  thesis,"  he  says,  "assumes  that  there 
are  two  classes  and  that  they  are  of  coordinate  rank."  Everything 
with  which  conscious  activity  comes  into  contact  is  valuable  from 
both  the  contributory  and  immediate  points  of  view.  But  it  is  only 
the  contributory  values  that  are  objective.  His  position  may  be 
described  as  a  polemic  against  the  subordination  of  instrumental  to 
intrinsic  values,  and  against  the  supposed  objectivity  of  intrinsic 
values.  Starting  with  points  that  are  matters  of  general  agreement, 
namely  that  all  contributory  values  are  objective,  some  immediate 
values  are  subjective,  his  own  conclusion  is  that  all  immediate  values 
are  subjective  (p.  4). 

It  is  with  the  second  part  of  his  polemic  that  the  larger  part  of 
the  book  is  concerned.  The  disproof  of  immediate  objective  values  in 
the  three  spheres  of  morals,  esthetics  and  logic  is  necessary,  but  it 
becomes  of  the  first  importance  to  disprove  the  theory  that  truth 
is  an  immediate  value.  For  the  general  question  "Windelband  's 
theory  of  norms  is  taken,  for  the  more  specific,  Kickert's  theory 
of  truth.  Mr.  Picard  has  done  a  useful  service  in  his  con- 
scientious critical  study  of  these  two  value  philosophies,  a  genuine 
understanding  of  which,  especially  of  the  latter,  is  signally  lacking 
in  American  philosophy.  There  is  nothing  distinctively  new  in  this 
criticism,  and  his  apparent  lack  of  acquaintance  with  the  1915  edition 
of  Rickert's  Oegenstand  der  ErJcentniss  unfortunately  vitiates  much 
of  his  criticism  so  far  as  it  applies  to  that  writer.  He  charges  both 


64  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

philosophers  with  inconsistency  and  errors  of  method  and  in  that 
charge  he  is  undoubtedly  to  a  degree  justified.  The  element  of  psy- 
chologismus  in  both  of  them  has  been  pointed  out  repeatedly. 
Rickert,  he  finds,  adopts  the  position  that  truth  and  reality  depend 
upon  a  transcendental  Sollen,  but  he  assumes  the  knowledge  of  cer- 
tain facts,  psychological,  in  order  to  prove  this  dependence.  Windel- 
band  does  the  same  thing.  Yet  to  show  internal  inconsistency  and 
error  in  method  does  not  disprove  the  truth  of  the  position,  and  it  can 
not  be  said  that  Mr.  Picard  has  disproved  it.  Indeed,  in  one  place 
he  says  (p.  177),  "our  attack  is  not  so  much  an  attack  on  the  theory 
that  there  are  objective  norms  of  thinking,  feeling,  willing,  as  an 
attack  on  the  attempt  to  demonstrate  the  existence  of  such  norms 
from  psychological  data."  As  to  the  charge  of  inconsistency  and 
error  of  method,  Rickert  at  least  escapes  it,  in  my  opinion,  in  the 
more  objective  method  of  his  later  book.  In  any  case  this  psycholo- 
gismus  is  not  inherent  in  the  position,  as  I  have  elsewhere  attempted 
to  show. 

On  the  other  hand,  Mr.  Picard 's  positive  contention  that  all  ob- 
jective values  are  contributory  and  do  not  depend  upon  immediate 
or  intrinsic  values  for  their  objectivity,  leads  to  some  curious  con- 
sequences. "Strange  as  it  may  seem,"  he  writes,  "the  judgment 
that  a  vase  is  immediately  beautiful  will  be  found  to  be  of  contribu- 
tory value"  (p.  17).  Apparent  judgments  of  objective  intrinsic 
value  retain  their  objectivity  by  being  forced,  in  pragmatic  fashion, 
into  the  instrumental  mold.  This  is  possible,  I  think,  only  by  a 
confusion,  inherent  in  all  pragmatic  discussions  of  this  question,  of 
instrumental  (in  the  sense  of  objective  relation  or  means  to  ends) 
with  contributory  (in  the  sense  of  adding  to  the  functioning  of  con- 
scious activity).  It  is  in  this  latter  sense  only  that  all  judgments 
of  value  may  be  said  to  be  contributory.  This  confusion  of  the  judg- 
ment of  value  as  contributory  with  the  judgment  of  contributory 
value  leads,  of  course,  to  the  denial  of  judgments  of  immediate  value. 
Mr.  Picard  thinks  that  such  judgments  are  only  apparent  and  due 
merely  to  the  fact  that  "it  is  possible  to  use  the  cognitive  function 
of  conscious  activity  to  express  in  thought  and  language  facts  of 
immediate  value."  The  "value  judgment"  is  a  large  question  into 
which  we  can  not  go  here.  It  must  suffice  to  recall  the  main  conten- 
tion of  the  opponents  of  his  view — namely,  that  value,  as  merely 
felt  and  not  acknowledged  in  judgment,  is  not  a  value  in  any  philo- 
sophical sense.  It  is  merely  a  psychological  fact,  a  part  of  existence. 

In  this  concluding  chapter  Mr.  Picard  leaves  the  way  open  for 
a  philosophy  or  metaphysics  of  value  in  a  fashion  which,  while  per- 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  55 

haps  not  wholly  consistent  with  his  Pragmatism,  is  none  the  less 
admirable.  In  this  connection  it  may  perhaps  be  permitted  to  take 
note  of  the  author's  reference  to  the  present  writer  in  his  preface. 
The  " subjective  point  of  departure,"  the  "psychological  position," 
ascribed  to  me  applies  only  to  an  early  work  specifically  designed 
to  introduce  the  English-speaking  public  to  that  phase  of  value 
theory.  That  this  scarcely  represents  my  present  position  must  be 
obvious  to  those  who  have  followed  the  later  developments  in  this 
field.  Insistence  upon  my  present  "objective,  non-psychological" 
point  of  view  has  value  in  this  connection  only  because  this  develop- 
ment in  the  present  writer's  thought  is  typical  of  a  fairly  constant 
tendency  in  value  theory  as  a  whole.  WILBUR  M.  URBAN. 

HANOVER,  N.  H. 

JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

SCIENTIA.  October,  1921.  The  Part  played  ly  different 
Countries  in  the  Development  of  the  Science  of  Radioactivity  (pp. 
257-270):  ROBERT  W.  LAWSON  (Sheffield). -A  history  of  radio- 
activity researches,  with  some  closing  remarks  on  the  question  of 
national  contributions.  The  major  contributions  havg  been  British, 
the  most  numerous  German,  then  follow  France,  Austria,  and 
America.  Le  probleme  de  la  luminosite  du  del  nocturne  (pp.  271- 
278)  :  CHARLES  FABRY  (Paris). -A  curiously  interesting  paper.  A 
diffused  light  is  responsible  for  the  degree  of  illumination  we  find 
in  the  night  sky.  Though  this  light  is  only  a  five-hundred-millionth 
of  the  intensity  of  sunlight,  yet  were  it  not  for  this  light,  we  should 
be  able  to  perceive  with  the  naked  eye  stars  of  the  eighth  magni- 
tude, or  ten  times  as  many  stars  as  we  now  perceive.  The  origin 
of  this  diffused  light,  whether  from  particles  in  nearby  space,  from 
faint  auroras  in  our  atmosphere,  or  from  untold  billions  of  indi- 
vidually invisible  stars,  is  still  a  mystery.  L' association  des  idees 
dans  les  reves  (pp.  279-296)  :  ERNESTO  LUGARO  (Turin). -Dreams 
are  neither  mere  associations  of  ideas  following  old  channels  nor 
the  symbols  for  hidden  desires.  In  dreams  the  emotions  are  stilled. 
The  abundant  originality  which  characterizes  the  sensory  picture- 
show  of  the  dream  world  has  never  been  sufficiently  emphasized. 
Though  there  is  almost  total  incoherence  to  the  succession  in  time, 
a  dream  taken  at  a  given  moment  may  present  sensorially  a  wonder- 
fully rich  and  coherent  picture.  Buts  et  resultats  coloniaux  de  la 
guerre  mondiale.  I.  Les  resultats  politico-territoriaux  (pp.  279- 
308)  :  GENNARO  MONDAINI  (Rome). -This  first  article  is  little  more 
than  a  compendium  of  facts  concerning  the  colonial  growth  of  Eng- 


56  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

land,  France,  and  Japan  due  to  the  war.     Reviews  of  Scientific 
Books  and  Periodicals. 

Brandt,  Lilian.    How  Much  Shall  I  Give  T    New  York :  The  Frontier 

Press.    1921.    Pp.  xi +153. 
Brunswig,  Alfred.    Einfuhrung  in  die  Psychologic.     (Philosophische 

Reihe,  herausgegeben  von  Dr.  Alfred  Werner,  34  band.)    Munich : 

Rosl  &  Cie.    1921.    Pp.  164.    M.  15. 
Bruhn,  W.    Glauben  und  Wissen.    Leipzig  and  Berlin:  B.  G.  Teub- 

ner.    1921.    Pp.  108. 

Eastman,  Max.     The  Sense  of  Humor.    New  York:  Charles  Scrib- 

ner's  Sons.    1921.    Pp.  257. 
Harrison,  Jane  Ellen.    Epilegomena  to  the  Study  of  Greek  Religion. 

Cambridge  University  Press.    1921.    Pp.  40. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

PROFESSOR  JAMES  JOHNSTONE  read  a  paper  on  "The  Limitations 
of  the  Knowledge  of  Nature"  at  a  recent  meeting  of  the  Aristotelian 
Society.  He  held  that  a  candid  and  impartial  survey  of  the  specula- 
tive biology  of  the  late  nineteenth  and  twentieth  centuries  must  force 
one  to  the  recognition  of  a  two-fold  passage  of  nature.  According 
to  the  fundamental  concept  of  physical  science,  the  second  law  of 
energetics,  viz.,  the  augmentation  of  entropy,  physical  change  tends 
continually  to  diminution.  The  universe,  to  use  Bergson's  term,  is 
detending.  To  the  biologist  there  is  another  aspect,  for  life  is  the 
incessant  attempt  of  certain  physico-chemical  systems  to  resist  the 
increase  of  entropy.  The  difficulty  in  accepting  the  main  result  of 
generalized  relativity  in  biology  is  that  for  speculative  physiology 
space-time  can  not  be  completely  isotropie.  More  especially  is  this 
so  if  with  Bergson  we  regard  the  quality  of  duration  as  the  cumula- 
tive continuity  of  life.  It  is  a  passage  as  well  as  the  persistence  of 
that  which  has  passed.  The  conclusion  of  the  paper  was  that  we 
must  regard  Newton's  "ocean  of  truth"  as  amorphous  in  structure. 
The  relations  that  are  to  be  discovered  in  it  are  only  in  it  in  the  sense 
that  they  come  into  existence  with  the  thought  that  makes  the  relation. 

Dr.  H.  H.  Bawden,  of  San  Ysidro,  San  Diego  Co.,  California, 
informs  us  that  he  is  disposing  of  his  library,  and  will  be  glad  to 
correspond  with  those  who  may  be  interested.  Among  his  books  he 
has  an  unbroken  file  of  the  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY,  which  he  values 
at  $90. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  3.  FEBRUARY  2,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


ON  THE  METHOD  OF  METAPHYSICS 

~TT\  VERY  metaphysical  theory,  whatever  its  type,  gives  primary 
-GJ     importance  to  one  pair  of  contrasted  concepts.     In  fact  we 
can  define  metaphysical  thinking  as  that  which  follows  the  making 
of  this  distinction,  and  which  attempts  to  make  explicit  the  full 
meaning  of  these  two  concepts  and  their  relation  to  each  other.    The 
discrimination  is  commonly  expressed  as  that  between  the  actual 
and  the  apparent,  or  between  the  existent  and  the  seeming,  or  be- 
tween the  real  and  the  phenomenal.    We  shall  employ  another  term 
which  has  some  important  advantages,  and  shall  express  the  distinc- 
tion as  between  the  real  and  the  given.    We  wish  to  know  the  nature 
of  the  real;  but  we  do  not  get  that  knowledge  easily  and  directly: 
we  must  begin  with  something  short  of  it,  and  must  approach  it 
through  an  earlier  acquaintance  with  something  which  is  original 
datum.    If  we  hope  to  reach  a  general  comprehension  of  reality  we 
must  found  it  upon  the  character  of  the  given.    Data  of  some  kind 
are  necessary  material  for  any  significant  theory.    We  accept  tM» 
as  true  in  every  science;  and  metaphysics  is  not  exempt  from  the 
same  condition.    Indeed  a  recognition  of  this  fact  is  of  primary  im- 
portance for  an  understanding  of  the  method  which  should  be  fol- 
lowed. 

From  this  underlying  distinction  it  seems  to  follow  quite  clearly 
that  any  complete  and  acceptable  doctrine  should  have  two  distinct 
parts,  which  we  shall  briefly  characterize  and  then  discuss  more  in 
detail. 

First  of  all  the  theory  must  offer  some  account  of  the  given  simply 
as  such.  This  part  of  a  metaphysics  would  be  entirely  free,  in  an 
ideally  successful  case,  from  anything  hypothetical.  Certain  data 
must  be  possessed,  and  must  be  granted  as  a  foundation,  if  any 
ontological  structure  is  to  be  raised  at  all.  A  statement  of  this 
original  material  ought  to  be  possible  without  the  admixture  of 
any  speculative  and  dubious  factors.  The  natural  scientists  have 
accustomed  us  to  a  requirement  of  this  kind.  An  impartial  state- 
ment of  any  facts  which  are  to  be  explained  is  a  proper  introduction 
to  the  statement  of  some  theory  which  undertakes  to  make  these  facts 
more  intelligible.  In  the  problem  of  color-vision,  for  instance,  there 
is  a  collection  of  phenomena  which  can  be  stated  quite  independently 

57 


58  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  any  theory  which  may  be  held  concerning  the  retinal  process. 
If  the  data  were  not  formulated  in  the  first  place,  without  any 
speculative  interpretation  being  allowed  to  slip  into  the  account, 
the  difficulty  of  finding  an  adequate  theory  would  of  course  be  im- 
mensely increased.  This  same  ideal  should  hold  in  metaphysics. 
However  difficult  it  may  be  in  practise,  the  first  aim  should  be  a 
strictly  non-hypothetical  expression  of  the  data  from  which  the  rest 
of  the  doctrine  must  be  developed. 

The  second  part  of  a  valuable  metaphysics  must  deal,  on  the 
contrary,  chiefly  with  hypotheses.  The  datum  is  what  it  is,  and  we 
may  suppose  that  its  essential  traits  can  be  expressed.  But  our 
problem  began  by  assuming  it  to  be  contrasted  with  something  we 
name  the  real.  A  metaphysics  could  have  no  use  for  the  conception 
of  a  reality  which  would  not  account  at  least  for  the  main  charac- 
teristics of  the  phenomenal  fact;  but  various  realities  may  be  con- 
ceivable, each  of  which  would  be  sufficient  to  account  for  these,  and 
this  range  of  possible  alternatives  must  be  examined.  If  some  of  the 
suppositions  which  we  find  ourselves  inclined  to  make,  or  which 
have  been  urged  in  historical  doctrines,  are  seriously  self-contra- 
dictory, then  of  course  that  must  be  made  plain :  the  incoherent  must 
be  simply  excluded.  If  a  theory,  otherwise  coherent,  is  incompatible 
with  some  part  of  the  given,  then  that  incompatibility  must  be 
observed  and  the  theory  must  also  be  excluded.  Should  only  one 
hypothesis  as  to  the  character  of  the  real  be  able  to  survive  these  tests, 
then  the  demonstration  of  that  fact  would  bring  our  ontology  to  a 
liappy  ending  in  a  last  chapter ;  and  a  last  chapter  would  be  a  happy 
•ending  in  itself.  But  if,  as  we  shall  consider  probable,  several  diverse 
suppositions  should  remain  tenable,  then  the  most  we  can  ask  from 
a  metaphysics  is  a  clear  statement  of  main  alternative  theories,  and 
a  recognition  of  any  non-logical  characteristics  which  may  fairly 
make  one  theory  preferable  to  another. 

The  data  which  should  be  formulated  and  described  in  the  first 
part  of  an  ideal  theory  are  of  course  not  to  be  identified  merely 
with  those  experiences  which  especially  arouse  us  to  the  problem 
of  metaphysics.  Striking  experiences  of  change,  deceived  expecta- 
tion, the  disappearance  of  something  from  our  world,  the  discovery 
of  conflicting  beliefs  about  the  general  character  of  the  world,  all 
these  challenge  us  and  make  necessary  the  distinction  between  the 
apparent  and  the  actual,  the  given  and  the  real.  In  a  sense  one 
might  say  that  these  are  the  special  data  for  the  metaphysical 
theory  to  which  they  impel  us.  But  its  original  material  must  in- 
clude all  that  constitutes  our  experience.  And  this  is  not  unavail- 
able nor  remote.  There  is  no  great  difficulty  in  becoming  aware 
of  our  datum,  however  difficult  its  adequate  and  pure  description 


ON  THE  METHOD  OF  METAPHYSICS       59 

may  be.  The  simplest  appreciation  of  it  comes  when  one  gives  up 
all  formulating  of  anything  in  words:  a  certain  "this"  remains, 
something  which  is  at  least  concrete  and  multifarious.  But  of  course 
our  formulating  is  a  fact  too,  as  it  occurs,  and  one  which  must  have 
its  own  place  in  an  account  of  the  given.  We  must  allow,  or  assert, 
that  some  actual  interpreting  of  the  data  is  itself  a  part  of  the  data. 
But  we  can  hardly  deny  that  the  possibility  of  reaching  a  metaphys- 
ical conclusion  depends  on  our  having  something  to  interpret.  With- 
out a  determinate  material,  which  could  be  expressed  as  empirical 
fact,  the  terms  phenomenal  and  real  would  be  equally  meaningless. 
And  to  say  what  this  material  is,  without  prejudice  to  any  hypo- 
thesis of  a  more  inclusive  and  trans-empirical  reality,  is  the  first 
problem  of  metaphysics. 

If  a  description  of  the  given  is  to  be  accomplished  at  all  it  must 
be  obtained  by  some  process  of  discrimination  and  analysis.  Any 
account  which  purports  to  be  descriptive  of  something  concrete  and 
individual  presupposes  that  abstractions  are  made  and  a  dissection 
performed.  The  possibility  of  this  analysis,  this  discrimination  of 
factors  or  traits,  is  difficult  to  deny  in  respect  to  anything  which 
is  in  a.ny  way  deseribable.  Even  a  Bergsonian  reality,  which  is 
asserted  to  be  not  portrayable  as  a  complex,  can  still  be  significantly 
described  by  such  various  adjectives  as  continuous,  active,  tense, 
and  so  on.  And  other  theories  which  undertake  to  deny  that  com- 
plexity can  be  accurately  predicated  of  the  real,  allow  nevertheless 
that  the  phenomenal  world  permits  discrimination  and  has  at  least 
''main  aspects"  which  accurate  thinking  must  recognize. 

Any  understanding  which  proceeds  by  distinguishing  and  by 
abstracting  must  aim  at  some  set  of  "primitive  ideas"  in  which  the 
analysis  could  terminate.  If  the  analysis  is  expressed,  some  set  of 
ultimate  terms  must  be  assumed,  individually  undefined  but  mak- 
ing others  definable.  So  the  most  non-hypothetical  account  of  the 
data  of  metaphysics  must  require  some  collection  of  concepts  which 
are  supposed  simple,  and  which  are  obtained  by  a  process  of  abstrac- 
tion performed  on  the  data  themselves.  We  are  inclined  to  believe 
that  there  must  be  some  one  particular  analysis  which  is  the  single 
and  only  right  means  to  an  adequate  comprehension  of  whatever  is 
being  analyzed.  But  there  seems  little  to  support  this  supposition. 
We  ought  not  to  take  for  granted,  nor  even  to  expect,  that  a  meta- 
physics should  contain  only  a  single  description  of  the  given,  and 
that  it  should  be  able  to  exclude  every  other  description  as  faulty. 
A  plurality  of  allowable  descriptive  formulations  is  the  more  reason- 
able expectation.  That  several  analyses  of  a  given  material  may 
be  equally  valid  and  practicable  is  strikingly  illustrated  in  the  field 
of  symbolic  logic.  Alternative  sets  of  primitive  ideas  may  be  em- 


60  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ployed  with  equal  success,  and  an  idea  which  is  adopted  as  undefined 
and  ultimate  in  one  formulation  may  as  properly  be  treated  as 
complex  and  analyzable  in  another.  The  simplicity  of  a  concept 
is  not  an  intrinsic  character  which  can  be  read  by  inspection,  but 
it  is  something  which  the  logician  postulates  after  experiment  with 
various  tentative  primitives.  And  in  metaphysics  we  surely  ought 
to  take  seriously  the  suggestion  that  the  data  which  form  our  material 
may  be  analyzable  with  equal  validity  into  more  than  one  set  of 
ultimate  terms,  and  may  be  describable  in  more  than  one  fashion 
with  equal  truth. 

One  expression  of  the  given,  one  first  broad  formulation  of  it, 
would  probably  pass  as  acceptable  to  most  common-sense  people  of 
our  time.  We  think  there  is  nothing  hypothetical  in  saying  at  least 
that  the  given  is  an  experienceable  world  of  nature  which  includes 
our  human  society.  But  we  must  examine  how  much  of  this  view 
can  be  retained  in  a  statement  which  undertakes  carefully  to  exclude 
all  hypothesis;  or  rather,  how  far  this  must  be  re-phrased  and 
translated,  if  its  meaning  is  to  be  put  into  a  strictly  positivistic 
expression.  Two  types  of  answer  may  be  mentioned,  characteristic 
of  divergent  theories  of  psychology  and  appearing  also  in  meta- 
physical doctrines  which  have  contemporary  interest. 

The  first  answer  would  be :  the  giyenjsui£jifin*nce,  and  experience 
is  known  without  hypothesis  or  interpretation  when  it  is  analyzed  in- 
to an  order  of  simple  qualities.  All  that  common-sense  finds  as  fact  is 
held  by  this  psychology  to  be  accurately  describable  in  this  fashion, 
even  of  course  one's  own  process  of  observing  and  analyzing.  This 
kind  of  psychological  analysis  is  evidently  employed  in  Russell's 
theory  of  the  physical  world,  with  its  doctrine  of  "particulars"  and 
of  the  humorously  named  ' '  official  biographies. ' '  His  elaborate  hypo- 
thesis of  perspectives  and  ordered  classes  of  private  spaces  is  thus 
actually  based  on  it.  But,  once  this  qualitative  analysis  of  expe- 
rience has  been  admitted  as  valid  of  sense-perceptions,  the  other  data, 
which  he  adopts  in  addition  to  the  particulars,  become  also  subject 
to  the  same  possible  treatment.  The  experience  of  being  acquainted 
with  a  universal,  for  instance,  is  part  of  an  actual  biography  too 
and  is  describable  in  the  terms  of  this  psychology. 

The  second  type  of  answer  is  that  which  appears  in  the  behaviorist 
psychology,  rejecting  the  qualitative  analysis  of  the  given  and  mak- 
ing its  own  description  in  the  terms  of  biological  science.  The 
philosophical  theory  represented  by  Dewey's  Reconstruction  in  Phi- 
losophy stands  on  this  ground  also.  In  the  reconstructed  description 
of  "experience,"  we  are  told,  "the  interaction  of  organism  and 
environment  ...  is  the  primary  fact  .  .  .  ."  That  the  datum  is 
of  this  biological  sort  is  not  merely  one  hypothesis  among  others, 


ON  THE  METHOD  OF  METAPHYSICS  61 

nor  a  hypothesis  adopted  simply  because  it  is  verified  in  use.  For 
the  nature  of  verification  itself  is  explained,  in  this  philosophy,  in 
terms  of  the  adaptive  responses  of  organisms.  This  biological  form- 
ulation is  not  offered  as  a  useful  speculative  interpretation  of  some 
data  which  could  be  properly  described  without  recourse  to  any 
such  speculation ;  it  is  presented  as  a  merely  descriptive  expression 
of  the  data  themselves. 

If  there  is  any  force  in  the  suggestion  that  several  non-hypothet- 
ical accounts  of  the  given  may  be  possible,  the  disparate  character 
of  these  two  types  of  description  should  not  be  taken  as  proving 
that  at  least  one  of  them  is  wrong.  But  some  quite  different  set 
of  primitive  ideas  may  be  more  successful.  An  account  of  the  given 
which  would  put  the  term  self  among  the  undefined  ultimates  is 
surely  a  competitor  with  the  others.  The  whole  problem  is  still 
open,  and  although  uncertainty  as  to  the  allowable  formulations 
of  the  data  upon  which  a  metaphysics  must  rest  is  undesirable 
enough,  at  any  rate  there  is  nothing  to  be  gained  at  present  by 
merely  assuming  that  only  one  formulation  is  allowable. 

We  have  been  taking  for  granted  that  the  given  is  something 
within  which  various  abstractions  can  be  made,  and  which  permits 
of  such  analysis  as  this  implies.  Without  this  character  the  pos- 
sibility of  analytic  comprehension  and  of  description  would  of  course 
be  lacking.  And  when  we  ask  that  our  metaphysics  should  contain  a 
purely  descriptive  part,  we  make  an  a  priori  determination  of  the 
given  to  this  extent. 

But  it  is  not  subject  to  any  such  elaborate  predetermination  as 
is  the  phenomenal  world  in  a  Kantian  theory.  All  Kant's  argument 
proceeds  as  the  analysis  of  a  certain  concept  of  experience ;  and  this 
concept  is  simply  postulated.  If  we  postulate  the  occurrence  of  a 
certain  type  of  knowing-of-objects,  if  we  make  this  our  fundamental 
fact  and  datum,  or  in  other  words  if  we  assume  that  the  datum  is  to 
be  described  as  a  knowing  of  a  specified  kind,  then  indeed  we  can  ob- 
tain some  a  priori  characteristics  of  objects  knowable  in  this  way. 
The  summary  description  of  the  experience  can  be  expanded  into 
a  series  of  analytic  judgments  which  merely  make  explicit  the  pecul- 
iarities of  this  postulated  knowing ;  and  from  these  judgments  we  can 
deduce  some  of  the  characteristics  which  must  be  possessed  by 
anything  which  can  be  known  in  this  particular  fashion.  But  such 
assertions  as  that  all  experienceable  objects  must  be  temporal  and 
spatial,  and  must  consist  of  something  which  endures  through  all 
change,  are  in  this  case  merely  drawn  out  of  the  postulated  character 
of  the  process  concerned,  and  are  analytic  judgments.  There  is  no 
way  whatever  of  compelling  any  one  to  agree  that  the  given  is 
actually  an  object-knowing  of  this  specified  type.  One  can  express 


62  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

what  one  finds  the  given  to  be,  and  if  it  is  finally  formulated  as  a 
something-known-in-a-specified-way,  then  the  concept  of  this  type 
of  experience  can  be  analytically  expressed.  But  the  occurrence 
of  this  particular  kind  of  experience  is  entirely  a  question  of  fact. 

If  we  assume  that  a  purely  descriptive  account  of  the  given  is 
possible,  we  still  have  to  consider  how  wide  a  range  of  significance 
could  be  claimed  for  the  primitive  ideas  required  in  it.  They  would 
have  one  meaning  as  abstractions  from  the  given  fact  itself.  Is  it 
possible  that  they  would  have  also  a  much  larger  application  t  Could 
they  be  used  to  give  us  some  knowledge  of  a  trans-empirical  reality, 
perhaps  of  one  from  which  the  given  would  be  logically  derivable! 

It  is  fairly  clear  that  we  could  not  attribute  any  such  importance 
to  these  ideas.  Suppose  that  an  analysis  of  the  merely  given  had 
been  completed,  and  that  a  collection  of  terms  had  been  reached 
which  were  adopted  for  that  description  as  undefined  and  simple. 
In  some  other  description  they  might  conceivably  be  considered  as 
complex  and  analyzable;  but  so  long  as  we  stick  to  any  single 
description  we  could  not  treat  any  one  of  them  as  a  possible  source 
of  others.  It  is  not  possible  that  any  final  term  in  a  systematic 
formulation  of  the  given  could  be  taken  as  the  concept  of  a  meta- 
physical entity  from  which  the  concrete  given  would  follow  as  a 
logical  implication.  The  complex  concept  of  the  phenomenal  fact 
can  not  be  deduced  from  any  item  which  a  purely  descriptive  ex- 
pression of  the  phenomenal  may  require:  the  analysis  of  the  given 
can  not  disclose  any  logical  source  of  it.  Within  experience  we 
can  not  find  any  origin  of  experience.  No  concept  obtained  in  the 
abstraction-process  could  be  known  to  have  any  applicability  except 
within  the  given  itself.  And,  if  our  metaphysics  is  to  contain  any- 
thing more  than  a  purely  descriptive  expression  of  the  phenomenal, 
that  additional  content  must  be  essentially  hypothetical  and  specu- 
la^ve. 

There  is  no  obligation  which  would  compel  a  person  to  carry  his 
theory  of  the  given  beyond  a  simply  positivistic  description  such  as 
we  have  been  supposing.  And  there  is  no  obligation  to  attempt  even  a 
description.  Abstractions  are  required  by  any  one  who  wishes  to 
know  abstractly ;  but  without  that  purpose  they  are  not  required  at 
all.  It  might  be  objected,  in  behaviorist  terms,  that  abstractions 
are  required  constantly  by  any  organism  which  is  to  survive,  since 
selective  responses  are  a  condition  of  its  keeping  alive.  But  we  need 
not  commit  ourselves  to  this  biological  description.  And  we  may  be 
sure  that  the  mm-occucrence  of  a  conceptual  understanding  would 
not  annihilate  the  given.  The  mystics  have  a  right  to  imagine  this 
absence  of  abstract  comprehension,  and  to  produce  it  so  far  as  they 
can.  If  the  resulting  experience  is  enlightening,  however,  the  en- 


ON  THE  METHOD  OF  METAPHYSICS  63 

lightenment  must  apparently  remain  incommunicable :  what  can  not 
be  conceived  can  hardly  be  described. 

But  the  mystic  state  may  be  assumed  a  very  rare  accomplishment ; 
actually  we  do  dissect  our  world,  and  do  use  abstractions  in  compre- 
hending it.  Actually,  also,  we  would  not  be  satisfied  with  a  philos- 
ophy which  consisted  in  a  mere  description  of  phenomena.  As  meta- 
physics begins  in  the  conviction  that  th^given^is  to  be  distinguished 
from  the^realjjso  we  are  led  to  make  a  hypothetical  ^7t^Tlgi^T1  of  the 
gi\en,  and  to  suppose  a  more  inclusive  fact.  All  metaphysical  think- 
ing postulates  this ;  and  even  the  positivists  and  empiricists  have  in 
fact  allowed  their  accounts  of  the  world  to  contain  a  very  consider- 
able hypothetical  element. 

A  metaphysical  theory,  then,  ought  to  have  a  secon^part  which 
is  frankly  and  explicitly  speculative  in  character.  "We  can  conceive 
of  various  trans-empirical  reals;  and  we  can  see  that  there  are 
degrees  of  compatibility  between  these  several  suppositions  and  the 
phenomena  from  which  we  must  start.  The  problem  is  to  determine, 
so  far  as  we  can,  what  types  of  reality  would  be  consistent  with  the 
given  as  we  find  it  to  be,  what  various  kinds  of  being  might  have 
this  actual  seeming.  So  long  as  we  avoid  self-contradiction  in  our 
assumptions  we  may  surely  use  the  greatest  freedom  in  tentative 
and  experimental  suppositions,  and  may  assume  a  reality  of  any 
imaginable  extent  or  variety.  There  would  be  more  fault  in  re- 
stricting hypotheses  to  traditional  forms  than  in  encouraging  the 
most  unchecked  speculation.  Men  have  probably  suffered  more  from 
too  limited  a  conception  of  possibilities  than  from  too  credulous  an 
acceptance  of  mere  speculations. 

In  the  problem  of  a  pure  description  we  were  led  to  suppose 
that  more  than  one  may  be  practicable;  and  in  the  problem  of  the 
hypothetical  interpretation  we  find  a  somewhat  similar  situation. 
We  take  for  granted  that  there  is  some  unique  and  all-inclusive 
reality ;  but  we  should  be  slow  to  assume  that  the  gjvjm  is  sufficient 
to  carry  us  very  far  in  determining  its  character.  Certainly  for 
the  present,  and  while  a  satisfactory  statement  of  the  data  is  still 
in  question,  we  are  very  far  from  any  narrowly  specified  concept  of 
a  reality  which  alone  is  compatible  with  them. 

There  are,  broadly,  two  main  divergent  developments  which  a 
speculative  metaphysical  theory  may  take.  In  a  theory  of  one  type, 
of  which  James's  radical  empiricism  may  serve  as  an  instance,  the 
real  is  supposed  to  be  immensely  more  inclusive  than  the  given,  yet 
is  supposed  to  be  simply  more  of  the  same  sort.  The  distinction  is 
between  a  part  and  the  whole,  rather  than  between  one  kind  of 
being  and  an  essentially  different  kind.  The  other  type  of  theory 
may  be  illustrated  by  Berkeley's  doctrine  of  ideas  and  spirits: 


64  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

there  is  supposed  to  be  a  reality  which  exceeds  the  given,  not  merely 
by  including  more  of  the  same  variety,  but  also  and  especially  by 
including  entities  of  a  radically  different  kind.     A  theory  of  this  J 
second  type  is  under  obvious  difficulties  in  drawing  up  a  description/ 
of  the  real  or  reals  which  it  assumes.     The  only  significant  terms' 
at  its  disposal  are  those  which  are  abstractions  from  the  given;  for 
the  only  source  of  the  meaning  of  our  words  is  in  our  concrete 
experience,  and  their  only  assured  applicability  is  to  it.    But  concepts 
can  be  constructed  which  are  not  descriptive  of  anything  given,  and 
they  can  be  supposed  to  have  some  kind  of  trans-empirical  signif- 
icance. 

If  this  is  indeed  the  situation  in  metaphysical  theory,  the  pre- 
sumption would  apparently  be  that  some  very  different  hypotheses 
are  equally  in  agreement  with  all  the  facts  we  have.  The  business 
,  of  our  theory  is  probably  to  discover  the  allowable  r^ge  of  sup- 
\  positions  rather  than  to  prove  a  certain  one  finally  true.  In  each 
of  the  sciences  we  have  found  that  in  general  the  known  facts  in 
some  problem  limit  the  number  of  possible  explanations,  but  do  not 
establish  any  single  one.  There  is  no  evident  reason  which  would 
lead  us  to  suppose  that  metaphysics  is  in  a  different  case.  The 
best  obtainable  result  may  be  a  set  of  mutally  exclusive  but  equally 
tenable  theories.  Take  the  hypothesis,  for  instance,  that  every 
event  is  a  required  part  in  the  fulfillment  of  some  all-inclusive 
design.  No  actual  occurrences  can  refute  this,  for  any  collection 
of  events  is  conformable  to  some  purpose  or  other:  a  teleological 
interpretation  is  always  possible  for  anything  that  happens.  But 
we  find  also  that  the  contrary  hypothesis  is  at  least  as  tenable, 
and  that  many  events  may  be  supposed  to  have  no  purposive  charac- 
ter. 

The  history  of  philosophy  consists  partly  in  a  series  of  demon- 
strations that  earlier  supposed  demonstrations  were  inconclusive. 
But  a  doctrine  which  fails  to  be  established  may  retain  some  value  as 
a  speculative  possibility.  We  hope,  of  course,  that  our  data  will 
lead  us  to  a  fairly  specific  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  reality :  but 
we  may  admit  that  a  group  of  very  diverse  hypotheses  about  it 
is  more  probably  accomplishable.  One  may  recall  the  answer  which 
Berkeley  received  to  his  appeals  for  the  payment  of  Parliament's 
subsidy  for  his  colony.  Walpole  replied  that,  speaking  as  minister, 
he  could  assure  him  the  grant  would  be  paid  in  due  time ;  but  speak- 
ing as  a  friend  he  advised  him  not  to  count  on  it. 

The  material  which  we  try  to  understand  has  its  own  definite 

)  character,  and  any  ontological  suppositions  must  be  adapted  "to  save 
the  appearances."    The  phenomena  are  the  first  essential  determi- 


ON  THE  METHOD  OF  METAPHYSICS  65 

nant  of  any  hypothesis  about  the  real.  But  it  may  be  useful  to  notice 
more  carefully  the  relation  which  exists  between  the  two. 

The  ideal  of  any  doctrine  about  reality  would  be  a  deductive 
system,  from  which  verifiable  conclusions  could  be  drawn  concerning 
phenomena.  Verification  is  not  wholly  an  affair  of  the  future. 
Present  phenomena  are  a  present  criterion.  If  we  can  say  what  is 
given  we  can  also  prescribe  some  of  the  deductions  which  a  satis- 
factory system  must  allow.  These  inferences  are  in  fact  simply 
begged  and  postulated,  in  advance  of  any  knowledge  as  to  how  we 
may  be  able  to  obtain  them.  We  must  assume  some  real  which  can 
account  for  the  occurrence  of  exactly  this  given.  We  try  to  find 
some  way  of  deriving  what  we  already  accept  as  fact. 

This  method  of  reaching  a  set  of  principles  is  commonly  dis- 
credited. When  we  discover  that  a  person  with  whom  we  are  arguing 
has  already  settled  on  his  conclusion,  and  is  merely  making  a  de- 
termined hunt  for  premises  which  will  justify  him  in  holding  it,  we 
are  inclined  to  be  scornful  of  his  procedure.  We  do  not  easily  admit 
that  we  ourselves  are  given  to  rationalizing  our  convictions  in  this 
way;  and  we  condemn  the  process  even  when  we  believe,  in  some 
particular  case,  that  a  man  practically  could  not  avoid  the  prejudice 
which  he  displays.  We  are  apt  to  think  that  our  metaphysics  ought 
to  be  free  from  any  trace  of  such  rationalizing.  But,  in  a  very 
genuine  sense,  no  theory  of  reality  can  be  free  from  it.  The  essential 
undertaking  is  to  discover  principles  from  which  would  follow 
facts  of  the  type  we  find.  To  understand  the  world  more  geometrico 
must  still  be  the  ideal  of  philosophy.  But  the  modern  theory  of 
mathematics  has  shown  more  clearly  what  a  geometry  is ;  and  another 
suggestion  for  metaphysics  may  be  derived  from  this  work. 

Not  until  recent  years  has  there  been  an  adequate  formulation 
of  the  primitive  ideas  and  the  postulates  which  underlie  the  old 
Euclidean  geometry.  We  know  now  that  the  postulates  of  this 
geometry  are  not  accepted  because  they  are  certain  in  themselves.  If 
they  are  considered  to  have  a  superiority  over  certain  other  alter- 
natives it  lies  in  this,  that  they  permit  the  deduction  of  some  theorems 
which  are  believed  to  be  more  useful  than  those  which  would  follow 
from  the  other  postulates.  The  theory  of  relativity,  however,  now 
seems  to  have  shown  that  the  Euclidean  theorems  are  inapplicable 
to  some  physical  measurements,  and  that  one  of  the  non-Euclidean 
geometries  is  always  applicable.  If  so,  the  postulates  which  go  with 
this  non-Euclidean  geometry  will  be  adopted  without  dispute,  or 
at  least  without  successful  objection.  In  themselves  Riemann's 
postulates  are  not  more  true  nor  less  true  than  Euclid's;  the  truth 
value  we  attach  to  them  is  dependent  on  the  practical  acceptability 
of  the  theorems  they  generate. 


66  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

A  similar  situation  exists  in  metaphysics.  If  we  could  get  a 
completed  doctrine  into  systematic  form  we  would  place  as  the 
postulates  of  the  system  a  set  of  propositions  which  had  been  reached 
by  a  process  of  experimentation  and  selection.  They  would  not  be 
given  their  place  in  the  system  because  they  were  intrinsically  true 
and  obviously  certain,  but  simply  because  they  would  furnish  an 
adequate  basis  for  the  inference  of  some  propositions  which  are 
simply  taken  for  granted  when  the  theory-making  begins.  We  can 
not  hope  to  find  any  ontological  principles  which  are  absolutely  self- 
evident,  which  can  be  recognized  at  sight,  and  whose  inherent  cer- 
tainty would  guarantee  the  certainty  of  their  implications.  Any 
set  of  assertions  about  reality  would  be  sufficiently  and  wholly 
justified  if  they  permitted  the  inference  of  empirical  facts  which 
we  already  hold,  and  led  to  no  inferences  which  are  contrary  to 
such  facts.  An  illustration  may  be  drawn  even  from  Bergson 's 
theory.  Suppose  we  could  properly  assume  that  a  simple  description 
of  the  data  already  includes  these  facts :  that  instinct  and  intelligence 
are  two  different  forms  of  knowing;  that  they  have  reached  their 
highest  development  in  insects  and  in  men,  respectively;  that  there 
is  a  constant  origination  of  new  forms  of  life ;  and  that  this  spatial 
world  is  predominantly  but  not  wholly  mechanical.  Then  the  as- 
sumption of  a  vital  force  such  as  Bergson  describes  (of  the  order  of 
consciousness,  active,  tense,  able  to  relax  its  tension,  etc.)  would  be 
plausible  just  in  proportion  as  it  could  be  seen  to  involve  the  occur- 
rence of  this  kind  of  a  world.  One  may  object  that  those  alleged 
facts  are  not  merely  descriptive  of  the  given,  and  that  they  already 
contain  a  hypothetical  interpretation  of  the  actual  data.  But  in 
Bergson 's  argument,  one  may  fairly  say,  they  have  the  role  of  data ; 
and  the  only  question  with  which  we  are  here  concerned  is  the  kind 
of  justification  which  a  proposed  account  of  reality  could  have.  If 
the  data  can  be  accurately  formulated  then  that  formulation  will 
evidently  be  the  touchstone  of  any  ontological  doctrine  which  may 
be  proposed. 

It  would  be  logically  possible,  as  we  said,  to  give  up  the  meta- 
physical problem  altogether,  and  not  to  contrast  the  given  with  any- 
thing. But  if  the  distinction  between  it  and  a  reality  is  maintained, 
then  the  only  account  which  we  can  produce  of  that  reality  must  be 
hypothetical.  A  positive  description  of  the  given  can  not  lead  us 
to  anything  except  abstractions  made  upon  it.  Analysis  can  not  dis- 
cover any  factor  in  it  which  somehow  again  contains  the  original, 
and  from  which  it  might  then  be  logically  deduced.  Any  theory, 
also,  of  the  type  which  holds  that  the  phenomenal  world  has  its 
source  in  a  mind  of  a  certain  sort  and  is  constituted  by  forms 
employed  by  various  faculties  of  this  mind,  is  evidently  hypo- 


ON  THE  METHOD  OF  METAPHYSICS  67 

thetical.  Like  any  other  hypothesis  it  must  first  be  tested  for  internal 
coherence:  if  we  deny  temporality  and  causality  to  this  mind  we 
must  consider  whether  it  can  be  supposed  to  operate  in  any  way; 
and  if  we  assert  that  no  other  objects  except  sensible  objects  can  be 
either  given  or  validly  conceived,  we  must  consider  whether  we 
can  know  anything  at  all  about  a  non-sensible  mind.  But  supposing 
that  no  incoherence  has  been  found  in  this  hypothesis,  it  must  seek 
its  confirmation  like  any  other  candidate,  by  allowing  deductions 
which  we  already  accept  and  which  are  part  of  a  description  of  the 
given. 

The  situation  which  we  thus  find  in  metaphysical  theory  is  similar 
to  that  which  has  recently  been  developed  in  logic.  The  validity 
of  the  classical  fundamental  certainties,  i.e.,  those  propositions  whose 
denial  implies  their  affirmation,  is  actually  undisputed ;  but  logically 
it  is  conditional  and  requires  the  assumption  of  a  particular  set  of 
postulates  for  our  logic.  Other  postulates  could  be  adopted  which 
would  not  require  the  truth-value  to  be  assigned  to  such  proposi- 
tions; and  these  other  postulates  could  be  used  without  violation 
of  consistency  as  they  would  define  it.  The  postulates  of  our  actual 
logic  are  accepted  because  they  validate  inferences  which  we  con- 
sider good,  and  not  because  they  themselves  are  separately  and  in- 
dividually indubitable.  We  have  to  work  backward  to  discover  the 
principles  which  we  are  actually  implying.  And  the  formulatiora 
of  an  adequate  set  of  primitive  ideas  and  postulates  for  our  logic, 
although  now  it  has  probably  been  accomplished,  is  not  even  yet  a 
matter  of  agreement  among  the  symbolic  logicians. 

In  our  metaphysics,  then,  if  we  can  obtain  a  description  of 
our  data  it  will  serve  to  limit  the  number  of  hypotheses  which 
can  be  held  concerning  the  nature  of  reality;  and  the  deducibility 
of  the  chief  characteristics  of  such  data  must  be  the  main  test 
by  which  any  proposed  ontological  doctrine  should  be  judged.  If, 
as  we  have  supposed,  it  should  prove  possible  to  make  more  than  one 
valid  description  of  the  given,  we  may  believe  the  number  of  tenable 
hypotheses  would  be  thereby  still  further  reduced ;  but  until  we  are 
more  certain  about  our  descriptions  we  can  hardly  take  for  granted 
that  the  specification  of  reality  can  be  carried  very  far  even  in  this 
fashion.  We  are  not  sure  how  to  express  the  given ;  and  we  are  quite 
sure,  when  we  stop  to  consider,  that  our  understanding  of  the  world 
is  partly  an  interpretation  and  a  supposition.  We  realize  occasion- 
ally that  our  active  beliefs  are  held  in  the  face  of  other  possible 
assumptions  which  have  quite  as  good  a  logical  standing.  It  would 
be  proper,  then,  for  a  systematic  metaphysics  to  give  some  recognition 
to  the  non-logical  features  by  which  some  hypotheses  acquire  a 
weighted  value  for  us.  Two  of  these  may  be  mentioned.  Some 


68  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

speculations  we  discard  as  wild  and  extravagant,  though  we  can  by 
no  means  show  that  they  are  inherently  impossible.  We  take  Occam  '9 
razor  as  our  best  implement:  not  to  destroy  all  hypotheses,  but  to 
insure  a  comely  simplicity  among  the  survivors.  At  bottom  the 
motive  for  this  is  esthetic.  Whatever  alternative  theories  may  be 
allowed  as  logically  tenable,  we  admit  a  differential  value  of  this 
kind  among  them.  Furthermore,  of  two  suppositions  which  are, 
so  far  as  we  see,  in  equal  agreement  with  the  data,  one  may  be 
actually  dispiriting  and  the  other  may  be  effectively  stimulating. 
Hypotheses  have  what  may  be  called  a  moral  aspect  as  well  as  an 
esthetic.  Great  individual  differences  must  be  recognized  in  the 
valuations  which  men  make  on  this  score:  the  whole  topic  leads  off 
into  psychological  problems.  But  one  is  justified  in  holding  that  a 
metaphysical  theory  may  properly  take  notice  of  all  the  main  features 
which  make  one  ontological  hypothesis  more  acceptable  than  another. 

CHARLES  H.  TOLL. 
AM  H  ERST  COLLEGE. 

CRITICAL  REALISM 

WHEN  The  New  Realism  was  published,  nine  years  ago,  some 
observers  professed  much  surprise  at  the  spectacle  of  phi- 
losophers laboring  side  by  side  in  a  common  cause,  without  any 
discernible  tendency  on  the  part  of  any  one  of  them  to  turn  upon 
and  rend  his  neighbor.  Since  then,  however,  the  achievement  has 
"been  duplicated  in  the  volume  entitled  Creative  Intelligence;  so 
that  the  philosophical  public  is  in  process  of  becoming  habituated 
to  the  phenomenon.  Whether  these  joint  undertakings  are  evi- 
dence, as  some  seem  to  suppose,  that  philosophy  is  at  last  to  enter 
upon  an  era  of  truly  objective  and  rigidly  impersonal  inquiry, 
after  the  manner  of  the  sciences,  or  merely  that  philosophers  pos- 
sess a  hitherto  unsuspected  capacity  for  cooperation,  is  still  a  ques- 
tion upon  which  it  is  useless  to  look  for  agreement.  The  latest 
volume  of  this  kind  is  the  recent  Essays  In  Critical  Realism,1  the 
purpose  of  which  is  to  expound  and  defend  the  realistic  faith 
which  the  contributors  to  the  volume  hold  as  a  common  possession. 
As  compared  with  the  earlier  books,  this  work  offers  a  compara- 
tively simple  programme  or  plan  of  campaign,  in  that  it  is  centered 
almost  exclusively  upon  the  nature  of  knowing.  Five  of  the  seven 
essays  are  devoted  to  this  topic.  As  is  stated  in  the  preface,  the 
authors  have  "found  it  entirely  possible  to  isolate  the  problem  of 

i  Essays  in  Critical  Ecalism:  A  Cooperative  Study  of  the  Problem  of  Knowl- 
edge. DURANT  DRAKE,  ARTHUR  O.  LOVEJOY,  JAMES  BISSETT  PRATT,  ARTHUR  K. 
ROGERS,  GEORGE  SANTAYANA,  ROY  WOOD  SELLARS,  C.  A.  STRONG.  Macmillan  &  Co. 
1920. 


CRITICAL  REALISM  69 

knowledge,"  so  that  it  is  with  reference  to  this  problem,  as  con- 
trasted with  ontological  problems,  that  the  collaborators  find  them- 
selves in  essential  agreement.  In  the  two  remaining  essays  the 
emphasis  falls  on  the  side  of  criticism  rather  than  construction. 
The  essay  by  Lovejoy  is,  in  the  main,  a  criticism  of  Dewey's  prag- 
matism: and  the  essay  by  Rogers  is  a  critical  review  of  various 
theories  regarding  the  nature  of  truth  and  error.  While  these 
essays  contain  much  that  is  of  interest  and  importance,  they  will 
be  omitted  from  present  consideration,  since  it  is  my  purpose  to 
discuss  more  specifically  the  doctrine  to  which  the  authors  have 
applied  the  name  of  Critical  Realism. 

As  was  to  be  expected,  the  authors  are  at  considerable  pains  to 
differentiate  their  position  from  other  forms  of  realism.  This  is 
done  by  emphasizing  the  distinguishing  feature  of  their  doctrine 
of  knowledge.  Naive  realism,  so  it  is  pointed  out,  made  the  mis- 
take of  supposing  that  physical  objects  could  be  intuited  directly, 
and  so  found  itself  unable  to  deal  with  certain  difficulties,  partic- 
ularly those  arising  from  the  relativity  of  sense-perception.  Copy- 
ism  escapes  from  this  difficulty,  to  be  sure,  but  it  is  obliged  to 
get  over  to  outer  existence  by  a  process  of  inference,  which  can 
be  done  only  by  a  tour  de  force.  Neo-realism  is  an  attempt  to  re- 
habilitate the  faith  of  naive  realism  in  the  identity  of  experience 
and  object,  but  it  is  obliged  to  construct  its  world  out  of  conceptual 
entities  or  essences,  which  gives  rise  to  various  difficulties,  espe- 
cially with  reference  to  the  problem  of  truth  and  error.  Each  of 
these  standpoints  contains  something  of  value,  which  it  is  possible 
to  conserve  through  a  reinterpretation  of  knowledge  along  the  lines 
laid  down  by  Critical  Realism.  Naive  realism  and  neo-realism  are 
correct  in  insisting  that  physical  objects  are  known  directly  and 
not  through  a  process  of  inference.  Copyism  is  correct  in  holding 
that  experience  and  object  are  numerically  distinct  and  not  identi- 
cal. The  reconciliation  and  justification  of  these  claims  are  the 
fruits  of  the  new  conception  of  knowledge  which  constitutes  the 
distinctive  trait  of  Critical  Realism. 

Stated  briefly,  the  doctrine  advanced  by  Critical  Realism  is 
about  as  follows:  Knowledge  takes  places  by  means  of  a  datum 
or  "given."  This  datum,  which  is  denoted  variously  as  "quality- 
complex,"  "character-complex,"  and  "essence,"  is  not  an  exist- 
ence, but  something  more  in  the  nature  of  a  meaning  or  what 
Bradley  calls  a  ' '  floating  adjective. "  "  By  the  essence  of  a  percept 
I  mean  its  what  divorced  from  its  that — its  entire  concrete  nature, 
including  its  sensible  characters,  but  not  its  existence"  (p.  223). 
This  doctrine  of  "essences"  is  the  central  feature  of  Critical  Real- 
ism. It  is  by  means  of  this  doctrine  that  the  position  undertakes 


70  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

to  avoid  the  errors  of  its  predecessors.  Since  the  essence  is  not 
an  existence,  it  can  not  be  identified  with  outer  reality,  after  the 
manner  of  neo-realism,  though  it  can  be  affirmed  of  outer  reality. 
Moreover,  this  affirmation  is  direct,  which  means  that  the  reality 
of  which  the  essence  is  affirmed  becomes  the  object  of  knowledge, 
as  against  the  assertion  of  copyism  that  the  immediate  object  of 
knowledge  is  a  mental  state.  To  put  it  differently  the  essence  is 
a  means  but  not  an  object  of  knowledge  (cf.  pp.  97,  189,  226). 
It  makes  natural  and  easy  the  transition  to  an  outer  reality,  which 
is  so  difficult  for  copyism;  and  it  maintains  the  distinction  be- 
tween content  and  object  of  knowledge  which  is  denied  by  naive 
realism  and  neo-realism. 

If  I  interpret  the  doctrine  correctly,  this  is  the  solution  proposed 
by  Critical  Realism.  It  is  a  solution  accepted  by  all  the  members 
of  the  group,  but  is  elaborated  particularly  by  Strong,  who  com- 
ments feelingly  on  the  great  significance  of  essences:  "As  I  have 
elsewhere  explained,  I  owe  this  precious  conception  to  Mr.  Santa- 
yana.  I  had  long  been  convinced  that  cognition  requires  three 
categories  for  its  adequate  interpretation;  the  intermediate  one — 
between  subject  and  objects — corresponding  to  the  Kantian  'phenom- 
enon* or  'appearance.'  At  one  time  I  used  to  designate  this 
category  as  content,  since  it  agrees  with  the  current  conception 
of  a  content  of  consciousness;  but  in  my  efforts  to  conceive  it 
clearly,  I  was  continually  falling  off  either  into  the  category  of 
object  or  into  that  of  'psychic  state.'  What  was  my  relief  when  at 
last  I  heard  Mr.  Santayana  explain  his  conception  of  'essence,'  and 
it  dawned  upon  me  that  here  was  the  absolutely  correct  descrip- 
tion of  the  looked-for  category"  (p.  224,  note). 

At  first  sight  the  theory  presents  an  appearance  of  engaging 
simplicity.  It  starts  with  the  tri-partite  division  of  mental  exist- 
ences, external  existences  and  essences ;  and  asserts  that  the  essences 
are  the  meanings  or  contents  through  which  the  external  existences 
become  known.  As  long  as  we  are  careful  to  insist  upon  the  status 
of  the  essences  as  floating  or  wandering  adjectives,  they  are  in- 
capable of  usurping  the  place  of  existences  and  offering  themselves 
as  the  objects  of  thought.  These  floating  adjectives  seek  an  an- 
chorage, which  is  provided  by  the  act  of  affirming  the  external  ex- 
istences to  which  they  pertain  or  the  nature  of  which  they  reveal. 
This  act  of  affirmation  is  much  more  fundamental  and  direct  than 
any  process  of  inference.  "The  sense  of  the  outer  existence  of 
these  essences  is  indistinguishably  fused  with  their  appearance" 
(p.  20).  "We  do  not  infer  a  realm  of  existence  co-real  with  our- 
selves but,  instead,  affirm  it  through  the  very  pressure  and  sugges- 
tion of  our  experience"  (p'.  195).  That  is,  essences  lead  on  "irre- 


CRITICAL  REALISM  71 

sistibly"  and  "instinctively,"  to  the  world  of  existents;  and  so  we 
escape  both  the  Scylla  of  copyism  and  the  Charybdis  of  hyposta- 
tized  meanings. 

It  soon  appears,  however,  that  this  doctrine  of  essences  needs 
to  be  handled  with  care.  On  this  point,  it  is  intimated,  there  is, 
unfortunately,  no  complete  agreement  among  the  Critical  Realists 
themselves.  This  issue  is  indeed  "the  one  question  in  our  in- 
quiry upon  which  we  have  not  been  able  fully  to  agree."  The 
statement  of  the  disagreement  is  relegated  to  a  pair  of  footnotes 
(pp.  4  and  20),  apparently  with  the  commendable  purpose  of 
keeping  family  squabbles  as  much  as  possible  out  of  the  public  eye. 
The  disagreement,  it  seems,  turns  on  the  question  of  what  consti- 
tutes a  datum  or  essence.  Three  of  the  seven  hold  that  the  datum 
or  essence  is  in  every  case  the  character  of  the  mental  existent; 
while  the  remaining  four  take  the  position  that  the  essence  may 
be,  so  to  speak,  composite  in  nature.  According  to  the  latter  view, 
the  essence  may  result  in  part  from  the  nature  of  the  mental 
state  and  in  part  from  the  function  of  the  mental  state  or  the 
use  to  which  it  is  put.  The  statement  of  the  difference  is  brief 
to  the  point  of  obscurity;  but  as  I  interpret  it,  the  point  is  some- 
thing like  this:  If  I  see  a  cushion  as  blue,  the  blue  is  an  essence 
or  datum.  The  mental  state  of  the  moment  may  include  the 
quality  'blue,'  which  is  referred  to  the  physical  object.  The  dis- 
senting three  hold  that  it  must  be  so  included,  since  this  is  the 
only  way  in  which  essences  can  be  obtained.  But  in  the  opinion 
of  the  second  group,  the  datum,  while  it  may  be,  need  not  be,  a 
character  of  the  mental  state.  The  latter  need  not  include  the 
quality  blue  at  all,  "as,  e.g.,  if  I  see  the  cushion  in  a  faint  light, 
when  it  is  nearly  black,  or  through  tinted  glasses,  and  yet  perceive 
it  as  a  blue  cushion.  So  it  is  clear  that  the  characters  that  make 
up  the  datum  depend  more  upon  the  associations  than  upon  the 
actual  characters  of  the  mental  state"  (p.  30).  The  actual  datum 
may  be  constituted  in  part  by  the  function  performed  by  the  mental 
state.  On  page  29,  at  the  end  of  an  illustration  intended  to  show 
that  the  characters  of  the  mental  state  may  be  very  different  from 
the  datum  or  essence,  it  is  said  that  "when  a  complex  mental 
state  of  the  sort  just  indicated  exists,  together  with  the  readiness 
of  the  organism  to  act  in  a  certain  way,  then  we  say,  and  feel, 
that  a  certain  datum  has  been  'given'  or  has  'appeared.'  This 
is  all  there  is  to  'givenness'." 

Perhaps  we  can  rest  content  with  the  earnest  assurance  that 
the  disagreement  is  not  a  serious  matter.  But,  even  so,  a  considera- 
tion of  the  disagreement  furnishes  an  opportunity  to  gain  a  further 
insight  into  the  meaning  of  Critical  Realism.  If  we  take  the  view 


72  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

that  the  essence  expresses  the  character  of  the  mental  existent,  we 
come  somewhat  closer  to  the  position  of  copyism.  If  my  mental 
state  must  "consist"  in  part  of  the  quality  "blue"  (whatever 
that  may  mean),  it  follows  that  sensible  qualities  are  "subjective 
substitutes  for  the  corresponding  parts  of  the  physical  world" 
(p.  191),  and  that  "the  content  in  terms  of  which  we  think  the 
object  must  have  the  property  of  reproducing  the  character  of  the 
object  in  some  measure"  (p.  198,  italics  mine).  This  is  certainly 
the  language  of  copyism.  On  the  other  hand,  if  we  take  cases  in 
which,  according  to  the  second  view,  the  essence  is  the  joint  prod- 
uct of  mental  states  and  their  function,  there  is  no  justification 
for  such  language  at  all.  The  essence  is  not  a  subjective  substi- 
tute and  there  is  no  process  of  reproduction.  In  appearance  at 
least  we  are  now  much  closer  to  the  standpoint  of  common  sense. 
Since  in  such  cases  "the  datum  as  a  whole  (the  total  character 
given)  is  not  the  character  of  any  existent"  (p.  21,  note),  atten- 
tion is  naturally  directed  away  from  the  conventional  notion  of 
reproduction  and  towards  a  consideration  of  function. 

Whether  the  disagreement  just  mentioned  has  any  serious  conse- 
quences for  their  position  is  a  question  which  we  can  afford  to  let 
the  Critical  Realists  settle  among  themselves.  My  purpose  is 
simply  to  point  out  the  shift  of  emphasis  towards  function  which 
the  disagreement  brings  to  light;  a  shift  that  a  pragmatically 
minded  reader  is  not  likely  to  overlook.  He  will  not  fail  to  notice 
that  if  "the  datum  as  a  whole  is  not  the  character  of  any  existent," 
but  is  determined,  in  some  measure,  by  the  behavior  of  the  organ- 
ism, the  import  of  this  doctrine  can  easily  be  translated  into  his 
own  familiar  language  of  stimulus  and  response.  The  "datum  as 
a  whole,"  he  finds,  varies  with  the  response;  and  there  is  little 
occasion  to  bother  with  the  metaphysical  "external  object"  of 
Critical  Realism  at  all.  "Data  are  directly  dependent  on  the 
individual  organism,  not  on  the  external  object,  varying  in  their 
character  with  the  constitution  of  the  sense  organs  and  the  way 
in  which  these  are  affected,  and  only  secondarily  and  indirectly 
with  the  external  thing"  (p.  225).  Moreover,  these  data  are 
symbols  or  signs  which  make  it  possible  to  ' '  rehearse  and  anticipate 
the  movement  of  things"  (c/.  pp.  170-173).  In  other  words,  the 
data  of  Critical  Realism  can  easily  be  induced  to  take  the  place 
accorded  to  objects  in  pragmatic  philosophy.  Datum  and  body 
vary  concomitantly,  and  the  process  of  experience  becomes  a  proc- 
ess in  which  we  "adjust  our  bodies  and  our  beliefs"  to  our  environ- 
ment (p.  30),  which  seems  to  mean  that  experience  is  a  constant 
quest  for  a  more  adequate  stimulus.  We  test  the  adequacy  of  our 
data  by  observing  how  they  work.  If  they  stand  up  under  the 


CRITICAL  REALISM  73 

test,  they  become  symbols  of  other  experiences,  which  is  to  say  that 
they  are  not  the  objects  but  the  means  of  knowing.  It  is  all  a 
question  of  further  experiences.  If  a  sense-observation  requires 
confirmation,  we  appeal  to  the  other  senses,  or  to  the  observations 
of  other  persons,  or  to  the  congruity  of  the  given  observation  with 
the  whole  body  of  our  past  experiences  (cf.  p.  106).  To  the  adher- 
ent of  pragmatic  doctrine  such  extensive  agreement  is  naturally 
a  source  of  considerable  gratification. 

To  the  Critical  Realist,  however,  this  agreement  is  of  minor 
significance,  since  his  chief  concern  is  for  the  "external  object." 
To  him  the  datum  is  not  merely  a  symbol  of  other  experiences,  but 
is  a  warrant  for  the  belief  in  an  outer  existence.  Just  how  the 
datum  functions  in  this  connection  is  not  altogether  clear.  It  is 
stated  that  we  pass  to  outer  existence,  as  it  were,  "instinctively," 
since  "the  sense  of  the  outer  existence  of  these  essences  is  indis- 
tinguishably  fused  with  their  appearance."  "Thinghood  and  per- 
ception go  together"  (p.  197).  Passages  like  these  suggest  that 
the  reference  to  outer  existence  is  somehow  part  and  parcel  of  the 
datum.  But  we  are  also  told  that  "when  the  datum  is  said  to 
exist,  something  is  added  to  it  which  it  does  not  and  can  not  con- 
tain— the  finding  of  it,  the  assault,  the  strain,  the  emphasis,  the 
prolongation  of  our  life  before  and  after  it  towards  the  not-given. 
These  concomitant  contributions  of  the  psyche  weight  that  datum, 
light  it  up,  and  make  it  seem  at  once  substantial  and  incidental. 
Its  imputed  existence  is  a  dignity  borrowed  from  the  momentum 
of  the  living  mind,  which  spies  out  and  takes  alarm  at  that  datum 
(or  rather  at  the  natural  process  that  calls  it  forth),  supposing 
that  there  is  something  substantial  there,  and  something  dangerous 
that  will  count  and  work  in  the  world.  But  essences  (as  Berkeley 
said  of  his  'ideas')  are  inert"  (pp.  179,  180). 

Contrasting  statements  of  this  sort  suggest  the  uncomfortable 
suspicion  that  the  harmony  among  the  Critical  Realists  is  attribu- 
table to  company  manners,  rather  than  to  inward  disposition  of 
mind.  Unless  the  language  is  misleading,  we  have  here  another 
cleavage,  besides  the  one  already  discussed.  On  the  one  hand  we 
are  assured  that  Critical  Realism  "looks  upon  the  total  content  as 
empirical,  and  is  sceptical  of  the  Kantian  theory  of  the  constitu- 
tive understanding"  (p.  211).  On  the  other  hand  we  are  met 
with  the  assertion  that  existence  is  a  "concomitant  contribution" 
with  which  the  psyche  weights  the  datum.  Whether  these  state- 
ments admit  of  reconciliation,  we  need  not  pause  to  inquire. 
Whether  apparent  or  real,  this  disagreement  likewise  may  be  used 
to  clarify  issues.  Just  what  are  we  to  understand  by  the  assertion 
that  the  affirmation  of  thinghood  or  existence  must  be  superadded 
to  the  content  of  perception? 


74  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Apparently  the  question  raises  a  dilemma.  If  an  additional 
element  is  superimposed  from  without  upon  the  content  of  the 
datum  by  the  affirmation,  we  get  Kantianism ;  if  nothing  is  super- 
imposed, we  get  an  empty  form.  Perhaps  these  two  alternatives 
have  not  been  kept  consistently  apart.  On  the  surface  the  state- 
ment that  there  is  a  "sense"  of  outer  existence,  which  is  "indis- 
tinguishably  fused"  with  the  content  of  the  datum,  appears  to  be 
intended  as  an  alternative  to  Kantianism.  But  if  so,  it  is  neces- 
sary to  ascertain  just  what  is  gained  by  the  manoeuver.  The 
sensory  qualities  are  already  "present"  by  virtue  of  their  status 
as  experienced  facts.  But  this  "presence"  is  not  what  is  meant 
by  "existence."  The  "sense"  aforementioned  requires  the  affirma- 
tion of  existence,  but  it  furnishes  no  content  or  meaning  for  ex- 
istence. It  does  not  warrant  the  conclusion  that  "the  special  and 
invidious  kind  of  reality  opposed  to  appearance  must  mean  an 
underlying  reality,  a  substance;  and  it  had  better  be  called  by 
that  name"  (p.  165),  unless  "substance"  is  taken  to  mean  "ex- 
istence" and  nothing  more.  But  bare  existence  adds  nothing  at 
all.  A  sensory  fact  which  is  merely  present  is  not  specifiably 
different  from  a  fact  which  has  the  affirmation  of  existence  added 
to  it.  As  Hume  says, ."To  reflect  on  anything  simply  and  to  re- 
flect on  it  as  existent,  are  nothing  different  from  each  other.  That 
idea,  when  conjoined  with  the  idea  of  any  object,  makes  no  addi- 
tion to  it."2  The  affirmation  of  this  ontological  existence  is  sup- 
posed to  be  vital  to  the  position  of  Critical  Realism,  but  an  ex- 
amination of  it  discloses,  if  a  Yankeeism  may  be  pardoned,  that  it 
is  the  little  end  of  nothing,  whittled  down  to  a  point. 

But  this  is  not  the  only  connection  in  which  the  problem  of 
existence  arises  to  trouble  us.  Correlated  with  these  "external  ob- 
jects" are  "mental  states."  These  too  exist,  although  "their  data, 
the  appearances  they  yield  me,  are  to  be  distinguished  from  the 
mental  states  themselves"  (p.  21).  The  belief  in  these  existences, 
however,  seems  to  rest  on  a  different  basis  from  that  of  the  belief 
in  external  objects.  The  appeal  is  not  to  a  "sense  of  existence," 
as  in  the  case  of  outer  existence,  but  is  rather  to  inference,  backed 
up  by  introspection  (cf.  pp.  25,  26,  234-237).  The  mental  states 
must  be  held  to  exist,  for  they  are  needed  as  vehicles  of  the  data 
or  essences.  Without  the  mental  states  we  should  be  unable  to  ac- 
count for  the  fact  that  data  are  sometimes  given  and  sometimes 
not  (pp.  26,  233).  When  we  introspect,  these  states,  ordinarily  un- 
noticed, come  to  light.  "I  admit  that  an  unfelt  sensation,  in  the 
sense  in  which  the  word  sensation  is  ordinarily  used,  is  absurd;  but 

2  Treatise  of  Human  Nature,  Part  II,  section  VI. 


CRITICAL  REALISM  75 

I  persist  in  thinking  that  that  which  we  feel,  when  we  feel,  i.e., 
distinctly  attend  to,  a  sensation,  is  capable  of  existing  when  it  is 
not  felt,  and  so  does  exist  in  all  vision,  hearing  and  touching  of 
external  realities"  (p.  235). 

The  claim,  then,  that  mental  states  are  the  vehicles  of  the  data 
is  intended  to  mean  that  the  mental  states  give  to  the  data  that 
peculiar  quality  of  "feltness"  which  distinguishes  the  given  from 
the  not-given.  Data,  to  be  sure,  are  not  felt  directly,  since  they  are 
not  existences.  "It  is  well  known  that  the  chief  factor  in  the  visual 
perception  of  distance  ...  is  convergence  and  accommodation  of 
the  eyes.  The  sense  that  distance  is  actually  felt  may  then  be  due 
to  the  fact  that  it  is  brought  before  us  by  the  muscular  sensations 
of  convergence  and  accommodation.  Distance,  in  that  case,  would 
be  felt,  but  not  visually  felt.  And  the  instance  would  constitute  a 
beautiful  example  of  the  way  external  objects  and  relations  are 
known  by  means  of  sensations  which  have  in  them  little  of  the 
characters  of  the  external  things,  but  are  simply  used  as  signs" 
(p.  236). 

It  will  be  recalled  that  copyism  is  criticized  by  Critical  Realism 
for  attempting  to  pass  from  the  given  experience  to  outer  existence 
by  a  process  of  inference.  The  same  criticism,  it  would  seem,  is 
applicable  to  the  attempt  to  justify  the  belief  in  mental  states  by 
a  process  of  inference.  Since  the  existence  of  these  states  is  not 
intuited,  they  are  as  much  "outer"  to  the  data  as  any  physical 
fact.  Does  it  become  known  to  us  in  precisely  the  same  way  ?  For 
example,  of  an  ordinary  perception,  in  which  a  blue  object  is  pre- 
sented, it  is  said :  ' '  Blueness  here  belongs  to  both  datum  and  mental 
state"  (p.  30).  The  reference  to  the  physical  object,  as  we  have 
been  told,  is  brought  about  by  a  "sense  of  outer  existence."  Must 
we  then  resort  to  a  parallel  "sense  of  inner  existence,"  which  is 
likewise  " indistinguishably  fused"  with  the  datum,  or  is  it  neces- 
sary to  resort  to  inference?  Two  such  "senses"  mixed  up  in 
one  experience  would  look  dubious  enough,  in  all  conscience;  while 
the  other  alternative  is  made  unattractive  by  the  horrible  example 
of  copyism.  But  waiving  this  point,  we  come  upon  a  further  ques- 
tion, What  is  a  mental  state  when  we  finally  discover  it  ?  Since  the 
given  consists  exclusively  of  ' '  essences, ' '  of  meanings  or  universals, 
it  would  seem  that  introspection  can  not  disclose  a  "sensation  of 
blue,"  but  merely  "blue."  That  is,  introspection  comes  upon  the 
same  datum  that,  in  the  original  perception,  was  assigned  to  the 
physical  object.  What  then  can  be  meant  by  saying  that  it  is  now 
found  to  be  the  character  of  a  mental  state?  The  only  difference 
that  is  introduced  by  introspection  consists  in  the  discovery  of  a 
different  context  for  the  blue.  It  is  now  found  to  be  associated  with 


76 

"sensation  of  eye  strain"  and  similar  introspective  material.  But 
this  does  not  convert  the  blue  into  something  mental,  or  make  the 
blue  a  clue  to  the  existence  of  a  mental  entity,  unless  this  connota- 
tion is  smuggled  in  with  the  word  "sensations."  While  we  speak, 
indeed,  of  "sensations  of  eye  strain,"  they  too  are,  by  hypothesis, 
essences  or  data,  and  their  reference  to  the  eyes  is  as  direct  and 
unambiguous  as  is  the  reference  of  blue  to  a  physical  object.  If 
we  classify  these  "sensations"  in  turn  as  mental  on  the  score  of 
their  associations,  it  is  plain  that  we  become  involved  in  an  endless 
regress  of  essences.  Critical  Realism  provides  no  content  for  the 
notion  of  mental  states;  which  is  perhaps  the  reason  why  it  is  not 
scandalized  by  the  suggestion  of  unconscious  mental  states.  If  we 
stick  consistently  to  the  doctrine  that  the  given  consists  of  essences, 
there  can  be  no  room  for  existences  of  any  sort,  and  both  external 
objects  and  mental  states  go  by  the  board. 

This  conclusion  is  emphasized  when  we  examine  the  function 
of  mental  states  in  giving  concreteness  or  vividness  to  the  essences 
which  enter  into  experience.  It  is  clear  that,  if  externality  is  made 
to  depend  upon  an  empty  reference  of  essence  to  existence,  it  be- 
comes necessary  to  invest  these  essences  with  the  "tang"  of  sensi- 
bility, by  virtue  of  which  they  become  transformed  from  plain  ab- 
stractions into  living  experiences.  They  must  take  on  "concretion 
for  discourse  and  for  action"  (p.  22).  This  process  is  supposed 
to  be  illustrated  by  Strong's  "beautiful  example"  of  the  muscular 
sensations  of  convergence  and  accommodation  which  give  us  the  ap- 
pearance of  visual  distance.  "The  datum  is  sensibly  vivid  be- 
cause it  is  brought  before  us  by  a  sensation"  (p.  237.  Unfortu- 
nately the  illustration  fails  to  illustrate.  The  datum  being  what  it 
is,  how  can  vividness  apply  to  it?  "A  meaning  here  is  not  to  be 
understood  as  a  peculiar  kind  of  feeling  that  can  be  met  with 
introspectively  in  the  same  way  that  a  visual  sensation  or  a  pain 
can,  but  as  a  function  which  the  feeling  dicharges  in  bringing  us 
into  mental  relation  to  an  external  thing.  When,  having  a  sensa- 
tion caused  by  an  object  in  our  minds,  we  are  disposed  (in  virtue 
of  the  connected  nervous  arrangements)  to  act  as  with  reference 
not  to  it  but  to  the  object,  then  that  object  is,  in  so  far,  before  the 
mind  as  a  datum"  (p.  237). 

The  passage  just  quoted  seems  to  reveal  a  significant  inconsis- 
tency. Data  are  functions  and  so  can  not  be  met  with  introspec- 
tively, as  it  is  possible  to  meet  with  a  visual  sensation  or  a  pain. 
That  is,  a  visual  sensation  or  a  pain  is  something  different  in  kind 
from  data  or  essences.  If  they  are  not  essences,  they  must  be  ex- 
istences, yet  they  can  be  the  objects  of  our  immediate  apprehension. 
"There  are  states  of  our  sensibility  which  do  not  bring  before  us 


CRITICAL  REALISM  77 

objects  other  than  themselves — e.g.,  anger  or  pain,  or  in  some  cases, 
chill"  (p.  233).  How  this  squares  with  the  doctrine  that  existence 
is  never  given  directly,  I  am  unable  to  make  out.  A  little  reflection 
will  show,  however,  that  the  general  position  requires  some  con- 
cession in  this  matter  of  sensations.  A  rigid  adherence  to  the  doc- 
trine of  essences  would  leave  no  room  for  vividness  at  all.  Vivid- 
ness must  come  in,  not  as  a  meaning,  but  as  something  immediately 
"felt,"  something  that  "constitutes  its  own  object."  If  we  were 
to  limit  our  consideration  of  sensations  to  essences  referred  to 
mental  states,  as  the  theory  requires,  the  whole  procedure  would 
remain  coldly  logical.  Since  Critical  Realism  ignores  the  sug- 
gestion that  givenness  may  be  connected  with  the  functioning  of 
the  "essence,"  and  not  of  the  "mental  state,"  it  can  account  for 
the  warmth  and  intimacy  of  sensory  experience  only  by  lapsing 
into  the  standpoint  of  traditional  subjectivism,  and  it  finds  itself 
obliged  to  give  new  life  to  the  dismal  theory  of  unconscious  mental 
states,  which  seemed  in  process  of  dissolution.  The  whole  situation 
seems  to  be  just  another  phase  of  the  historic  difficulty  about 
sensations  and  relations;  and  the  best  we  get  is  the  unintelligible 
assurance  that  "a  datum  can  be  so  concrete  as  even  to  have  sensible 
vividness,  and  yet  not  be  an  existence,  but  only  an  entirely  concrete 
universal,  a  universal  of  the  lowest  order"  (p.  231).  How  low 
a  universal  of  this  sort  would  have  to  be,  it  would  perhaps  be  indeli- 
cate to  inquire. 

The  foregoing  criticism  may  be  summed  up  by  saying  that  the 
doctrine  of  essences,  which  constitutes  the  distinctive  feature  of 
the  position  and  which  is  relied  upon  as  an  alternative  to  both 
copyism  and  neo-realism,  works  havoc  in  the  end,  because  it  leaves 
no  room  for  existence  of  any  kind.  It  is  a  pleasure  to  concede  many 
merits  to  the  book.  In  view  of  the  nature  of  its  topic,  it  is  very 
readable.  It  possesses  many  keen  and  suggestive  analyses,  and  it 
is  undoubtedly  an  important  contribution.  But  that  it  offers  an 
acceptable  solution  as  it  stands,  I  am  unable  to  believe.  In  the 
presence  of  the  historic  tradition  which  requires  that  mind  be  iso- 
lated from  its  objects  by  a  gulf  which  can  be  traversed  only  by  a 
claim,  Critical  Realism  lays  aside  all  its  sophistication  and  shows 
a  striking  capacity  for  simple  faith.  But,  as  I  have  tried  to  show, 
the  book  itself  furnishes  certain  suggestions  as  to  the  lines  along 
which  an  acceptable  revision  might  be  made.  And  it  provides  ad- 
ditional evidence  for  the  view  that  the  "external  object,"  to  which 
Critical  Realism  attaches  so  much  importance,  serves  no  purpose 
whatever  except  to  give  a  certain  dignity  or  esthetic  sanction  to  the 
proceedings.  But  the  authors  have  succeeded  in  making  their 
position  as  plausible  as  the  materials  at  their  disposal  would  per- 


78  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

mit,  and  in  doing  so  they  have  done  much  towards  the  clarification 
of  the  important  philosophic  issues  of  the  day. 

B.  H.  BODE. 

OHIO  STATE  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Le   Thomisme,  introduction  au  systcme  de  8.   Thomas  D'Aquin. 

fiTEENNE  GILSON.    Strasbourg:  A.  Vix  et  Cie.    1919.    Pp.  174. 

It  has  become  conventional  among  historians  of  philosophy  to 
pass  from  the  Greeks  to  the  moderns,  from  Plotinus  to  Bacon  and 
Descartes,  much  as  if  between  there  had  been  no  speculating  on 
earth  "about  it,  and  about."  This  attitude  of  mind  is  grossly  pro- 
vincial. It  appears  to  be  taken  for  granted  that  the  great  school- 
men of  the  thirteenth  century,  because  they  were  theologians, 
could  not  be  philosophers ;  whereas,  remarks  Professor  Gilson,  ' '  une 
philosophic  qui  cherche  a  rejoindre  une  foi  n'en  est  pas  moins  une 
philosophic"  (p.  6).  Indeed,  to  him  the  thirteenth  century  ap- 
pears as  rich  a  philosophical  epoch  as  the  epochs  of  Descartes 
and  of  Leibnitz,  or  of  Kant  and  of  Auguste  Comte.  As  chief 
representatives  of  that  rich  period  he  cites  Thomas  Aquinas  and 
Duns  Scotus.  It  is  to  the  philosophical  system  of  the  former  that 
he  will  introduce  his  reader. 

This  system,  like  all  great  systems  of  philosophy,  resulted  from 
an  effort  to  harmonize  divergent  spiritual  tendencies  of  the  histor- 
ical moment.  In  a  few  broad  outlines,  Professor  Gilson  sketches 
the  antecedents  of  the  situation. 

After  Plotinus,  there  was  for  five  centuries  virtual  philosophical 
silence.  The  two  centuries  of  the  Patristic  period  were  altogether 
theological;  the  three  centuries  following  where  wholly  given  to 
practical  issues,  political  and  social  reconstruction.  Under  Char- 
lemagne this  task  was  fulfilled.  Under  his  aegis,  also,  revived  philo- 
sophical speculation,  thereafter  to  continue  to  modern  times  without 
breach  of  continuity.  During  the  next  four  centuries,  three  con- 
siderable conclusions  were  arrived  at,  all  three  fundamental  to 
the  Thomistic  synthesis:  (1)  recognition  of  the  parallel  validity  of 
reason  and  faith;  (2)  solution  of  the  age-long  problem  of  "  uni- 
versals  "  by  conceptualism  demonstrating  the  sense-origin  of  con- 
cepts; (3)  the  so-called  scholastic  method  of  argumentation  by  enum- 
eration of  arguments  contra,  development  of  the  solution  proposed, 
refutation  of  objections  already  raised. 

Opinion  in  this  period,  on  the  other  hand,  wavered  uncertainly  be- 
tween Plato  and  Aristotle  without  clearly  understanding  either.  Of 
Aristotle,  especially,  only  the  Organon  was  directly  accessible.  What 


BOOK  REVIEWS  79 

therefore  wholly  altered  the  situation  were  the  Toledan  translations 
of  the  Physics  and  Metaphysics,  Avicenna's  abridgment,  and 
Averroes'  commentary,  all  divulgated  at  the  beginning  of  the 
thirteenth  century.  But  the  Peripatetic  system,  now  at  last  revealed 
in  its  wholeness,  seemed  to  deny  Christian  faith  in  divine  providence 
and  the  immortality  of  the  individual  human  soul. 

In  consequence,  Christian  opinion  again  split.  One  faction,  voiced 
principally  by  the  Franciscan  St.  Bonaventure,  asserted  fundamental 
antagonism  between  the  new  Aristotle  and  Christian  dogma.  Aris- 
totle's basic  error  lay  for  them  in  his  rejection  of  Plato's  doctrine 
of  Ideas.  If  God  possessed  not  in  himself  the  Ideas  of  all  things 
as  exemplars,  he  must  know  himself  only,  and  not  particulars ;  which 
negates  divine  providence.  Moreover,  oblivious  of  his  world,  God 
could  not  have  created  it.  Therefore  it  must  be  eternal.  If  eternal, 
there  must  have  existed  in  it  an  infinity  of  men,  and  so  there  must 
be  an  infinity  of  souls ;  unless  indeed  the  soul  is  corruptible,  or  the 
same  souls  pass  from  body  to  body,  or  there  is  but  one  soul — or 
intellect — for  all  men.  According  to  Averroes,  Aristotle  accepted 
the  last  choice.  Hence,  obviously,  Aristotle  would  deny  the  possi- 
bility of  individual  immortality  and  of  future  reward  and  punish- 
ment. St.  Bonaventure  and  his  group,  accordingly,  rejected  Aris- 
totle and  all  his  works,  and  clung  to  the  traditional  Platonic- 
Augustinian  exemplarism. 

Another  faction,  in  despair,  renounced  speculation  by  reason 
altogether,  so  setting  up  again  the  barrier  between  reason  and 
faith.  At  the  other  extreme,  a  not  inconsiderable  group  of  in- 
tellectual radicals,  defying  imputation  of  heresy,  accepted  the 
Averroistic  Aristotle  in  toto. 

Against  the  anathema  of  the  Church,  these  radicals  could  not 
prevail ;  but  the  very  boldness  of  their  stand  in  the  name  of  reason 
was  a  warning.  The  manifest  superiority  of  Aristotle's  natural 
science  assured  its  ultimate  acceptance.  If  his  metaphysics  could 
be  conformed  to  Christian  dogma,  that  dogma  would  be  the  more 
strengthened  by  sponsoring  his  triumphant — and  innocuous — 
physical  doctrines.  Otherwise,  there  was  danger  of  heresy  spread- 
ing. 

Specifically,  to  Christianize  Aristotle  it  was  necessary,  says 
Professor  Gilson,  to  ' '  reintroduire  dans  le  systeme  1  'exemplarisme 
et  la  creation,  maintenir  la  providence,  concilirer  1'unite  de  la 
forme  substantielle  avec  1  'immortalite  de  Tame  "  (p.  12).  The 
path-breaker  towards  this  end  was  Albert  of  Cologne,  called  "  the 
Great ;  ' '  but  although  encyclopedic  in  scope,  he  failed  to  achieve 
in  any  proper  sense  a  coherent  and  consistent  philosophical  sys- 
tem on  the  compromise  bases.  This  achievement  was  reserved  for 


80  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

his  disciple,  Thomas  Aquinas;  and  as  evidence  of  St.  Thomas's 
success,  Professor  Qilson  alleges  the  fact  that  "apres  six  cent 
ans  de  speculation  philosophique  et  malgre  des  tentatives  innom- 
brables  pour  constituer  une  apolog6tique  sur  des  bases  nouvelles, 
1'Eglise  vit  encore  de  la  pensce  de  S.  Thomas  d'Aquin,  et  veut 
continuer  d'en  vivre  "  (pp.  13-14). 

The  method  of  St.  Thomas's  conciliation  may  be  illustrated 
by  a  single  instance.  According  to  Aristotle,  a  future  contingent 
can  not  be  known,  for  as  soon  as  known  as  true,  it  ceases  to  be 
contingent  to  become  necessary.  But  to  refuse  God  the  knowledge 
of  future  contingents,  is  to  make  providence  impossible.  Aris- 
totle's conclusion  on  this  point  is  therefore  inadmissible.  Although 
disparity  with  dogmatic  truth,  however,  motivates  rejection  of 
Aristotle's  authority,  rejection  is  not  justified  until  reason  can 
find  support  for  the  opposite  conclusion.  St.  Thomas,  accordingly, 
demonstrates  by  logical  deduction  that  God  can,  and  must,  know 
future  contingents  (pp.  67-68). 

The  instance  is  typical;  and  from  it  the  generalization  may 
be  made  that  St.  Thomas  incorporated  into  his  system  Aristotle's 
positions  so  far  as  these  were  compatible  with  Christian  dogma; 
and  if  substitutions  were  made  in  the  name  of  the  Faith,  these  also 
were  logically  deduced  from  the  premises  of  the  system  itself.  So,  to 
repeat,  although  St.  Thomas  be  motivated  by  theological  considera- 
tions, he  still  achieved  in  the  strictest  sense  of  the  word  a  philosophy. 

To  evaluate  in  detail  the  outline  of  this  philosophy  given  by  Pro- 
fessor Gilson  is  beyond  the  competence  of  the  present  reviewer.  It 
is  at  least  delightfully  candid,  succinct,  and  clear. 

There  is,  however,  a  point  of  query.  Emphasizing  as  basic  to 
Thomism,  the  restriction  of  human  cognition  to  abstraction  from  the 
data  of  sense,  Professor  Gilson  declares  in  his  general  conclusion: 
"Le  platonisme  trouvait  dans  la  mystique  son  dernier  achevement, 
et  il  faut  dire,  au  contraire,  que  dans  la  mesure  oil  la  mystique  sup- 
poserait  une  intuition,  et  comme  une  experience  directe  de  Dieu  par 
1'ame,  le  thomisme  constitue  la  negation  radicale  de  la  mystique  " 
(pp.  171-172).  Perhaps  in  consistency  this  should  be  true;  but 
St.  Thomas  was  confronted  with  the  case  of  St.  Paul  (II  Cor.  xii), 
and  unqualifiedly  concludes  that  the  Apostle  had  in  "  rapture  " 
immediate  cognition  of  the  divine  essence.  (Cf.  De  veritate,  xii, 
2;  Summa  theol.  II-II,  clxxiv,  4.)  Now  obviously,  to  admit  the  pos- 
sibility of  even  a  single  "  experience  directe  de  Dieu  par  1'ame  "  is 
to  open  the  door  to  mysticism.  Instance  the  Thomist  Dante 's  claim  to 
a  similar  intuition,  which  may  be  poetic  fiction,  but  is  no  less  recog- 
nition of  the  mystical  potentiality  of  St.  Thomas's  doctrine. 

JEFFERSON  B.  FLETCHER. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  81 

The  Principles  of  Esthetics.    DE\VITT  H.  PARKER.    Boston :  Silver, 

Burdett  and  Company.    1920.    Pp.  v  -f  374. 

It  would  have  been  achievement  enough  to  have  produced  some- 
thing like  an  adequate  textbook  on  esthetics.  But  Mr.  Parker  has 
done  more  than  this.  He  has  written  a,  book  that  makes  profitable 
and  pleasant  reading  alike  for  those  unfamiliar  with  the  subject 
and  for  those  versed  in  its  traditions  and  literature.  For  purposes 
of  instruction,  The  Principles  of  Esthetics  must,  to  be  sure,  be  sup- 
plemented by  works  on  certain  aspects  of  the  subject  that  are  left 
entirely  untouched — as,  for  example,  the  matter  of  the  origins  of 
art.  But  this  deficiency  is  partially  supplied  by  references  in  the 
bibliography  appended.  Moreover,  the  matters  treated  are  quite 
numerous  and  varied  enough  for  the  compass  of  the  volume. 

Mr.  Parker  deliberately  stresses  psychological  esthetics;  or 
perhaps  it  might  more  properly  be  said  that  for  him  the  subject  is 
essentially  psychological.  "I  use  'experience  of  art'  'esthetic  ex- 
perience,' and  'beauty'  with  the  same  meaning,"  he  observes  (p. 
53).  This  bias  does  not  prevent  his  giving  in  his  later  chapters  an 
exceedingly  good  objective  analysis  of  the  structure  of  the  several 
arts,  taking  up  in  turn,  music,  poetry,  prose  literature,  painting, 
sculpture  and  architecture.  In  connection  with  the  problem  of 
evil,  he  considers  the  nature  of  the  tragic,  the  comic,  and  the  pa- 
thetic, treating  these  as  so  many  methods  of  solving  that  problem. 
The  last  two  chapters  he  devotes  to  the  relation  of  art  to  morality 
and  religion. 

The  book  is  essentially  non-historical.  To  but  a  small  extent 
is  even  reference  made  to  traditional  solutions  of  the  problems 
considered.  Mr.  Parker's  own  solutions  are,  of  course,  by  no  means 
uniquely  his,  but  in  his  handling  he  displays  vigor,  originality  and 
freshness.  Particularly  good  throughout  the  volume  is  the  treat- 
ment of  the  antithesis  of  thought  and  feeling  in  the  esthetic  ex- 
perience. Mr.  Parker  coins  the  word  einmeinung  after  analogy 
with  einfiihlung  to  express  "the  relation  of  the  idea  to  the  sense 
medium  of  the  expression."  "Feeling,"  he  observes  (p.  70)  "is 
a  function  of  ideas;  if,  then,  we  demand  sincerity  in  the  one,  we 
must  equally  demand  conviction  in  the  other." 

To  those  who  relish  a  sincere,  sympathetic,  and  human  treat- 
ment of  matters  which  may  be  made  either  too  abstruse  or  hack- 
neyed, this  volume  will  be  exceedingly  welcome. 

HELEN  Huss  PARKHURST. 
BAENARD  COLLEGE. 


82  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

SCIENTIA.  September,  1921.  Le  comete  secolari  ed  ft  moto 
del  Sole  nello  spazio  (pp.  181-188):  G.  ABMELLINI  (Padua). -It 
seems  highly  probable  that  all  comets  belong  to  the  solar  system. 
Even  if  a  comet's  orbit  were  found  to  be  hyperbolic,  we  even  then 
could  not  be  sure  it  came  from  the  remote  depths  of  space.  L1 'emis- 
sion d'electricitS  par  les  corps  incandescent*  (pp.  189-194) :  A. 
BONTARIC  (Dijon). -Under  the  influence  of  heat,  electrons  escape 
from  a  body  in  a  way  analogous  to  ordinary  vaporization,  and  this 
movement  of  negative  particles  constitutes  an  electric  current. 
First  studied  from  a  purely  theoretical  angle,  this  phenomenon  has 
now  given  rise  to  ingenious  technical  applications — showing  again 
the  unexpectedly  practical  value  of  highly  theoretical  inquiries. 
The  Chemical  and  Biological  Differences  in  Proteins  (pp.  195-200) : 
E.  H.  A.  PLIMMER  (Aberdeen). -Somewhat  technical  paper  point- 
ing out  the  inadequacy  of  our  knowledge  in  this  field.  La  question 
de  I'union  de  I'Autriche  allemande  a  I'Allemagne  (pp.  201-212) : 
BERTRAND  AUERBACH  (Nancy). -Purely  historical  sketch  of  the  re- 
lations of  Austria  to  Germany  in  the  period  just  before  the  Treaty 
of  Versailles.  Psycho-vitalisme  et  hypothese  mnemique  (pp.  213- 
217) :  "VERNON  LEE"  (Florence). -Review  of  the  work  of  Richard 
Semon,  defending  his  theory  of  organic  memory  as  truly  scientific 
and  not  obscurantist.  Reviews  of  Scientific  Books  and  Periodicals. 

de  Miranda,  Pontes.  A  Sabedoria  dos  Instinctos;  Ideas  e  Anteci- 
pac.6es.  Rio  de  Janeiro:  J.  Ribeiro  dos  Santos.  1921.  Pp.  238. 

Mitchell,  T.  W.  The  Psychology  of  Medicine.  London :  Methuen  & 
Co.  1921.  Pp.  187.  6  sh. 

Ralph,  Joseph.  How  to  Psycho- Analyze  Yourself :  Theory  and  Prac- 
tice of  Remoulding  the  Personality  by  the  Analytic  Method. 
Long  Beach,  California:  published  by  the  author.  1921.  Pp. 
318.  $5. 

van  Velzen,  H.  Thoden.  Force  Curative.  Geneva:  S.  A.  des  Edi- 
tions Sonor.  1921.  Pp.  30. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

CONFERENCE   ON   PHILOSOPHY   AT  THE  UNIVERSITY   OP  TORONTO 

Sir  Robert  Falconer,  President  of  the  University  of  Toronto, 
on  behalf  of  the  Department  of  Philosophy  extended  an  invitation 
to  several  prominent  leaders  to  take  part  in  a  conference  on  Jan. 
17,  18  and  19  to  discuss  philosophical  problems.  Some  of  those 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  83 

invited  were  ima,ble  to  attend;  but  a  sufficient  number  were  pres- 
ent to  make  possible  an  interesting  programme,  planned  to  secure 
a  presentation  and  discussion  of  contemporary  tendencies. 

The  proceedings  were  opened  by  a  general  statement  of  the  im- 
port of  modern  philosophy  by  Professor  Woodbridge  of  Columbia. 
He  developed  the  thought  that  at  first  both  medieval  and  modern 
philosophy  were  mainly  engaged  in  the  task  of  translating  earlier — 
especially  the  Greek — speculations  into  the  Latin  and  modern  lan- 
guages. Later  the  modern  philosophers  discovered  that  they  must 
get  beyond  terms  and  terminologies  and  explore  the  real  subject 
matter  of  philosophy,  i.e.  actual  human  experience.  Out  of  the 
earlier  effort  to  state  and  formulate,  and  the  later  one  to  explore 
and  investigate,  there  grew  up  a  healthy  rivalry  or  " criticism" 
which  has  kept  modern  philosophy  alive  and  moving.  Whether 
this  movement  is  a  forward  and  progressive  one  or  not  is  to  some 
still  a  matter  for  debate. 

Professor  Shastri  of  Calcutta  followed  with  an  exposition  of 
the  various  schools  of  eastern  philosophy  and  their  inter-relations 
in  a  manner  which  showed  his  intimate  knowledge  of  this  subject. 

In  the  evening  a  public  lecture  was  given  by  Professor  Hock- 
ing of  Harvard  on  "Philosophy  and  History."  It  was  skilfully 
shown  that  history  must  eventually  endeavor  to  interpret  events 
in  terms  of  mind.  When  certain  notable  changes  took  place,  not 
foreseen  or  humanly  planned  for,  it  was  once  customary  to  invoke 
for  explanation  Chance,  or  Fate,  or  Providence.  Later  on,  much 
more  stress  was  laid  upon  "economic  pressure."  After  analyzing 
the  elements  in  the  term  "economic"  and  admitting  its  tremendous 
significance,  he  pointed  out  that  these  economic  agencies  are  not 
mere  blind  forces,  utterly  uncontrollable,  but  that,  wherein  they 
succeed,  in  the  long  run  it  can  be  shown  that  this  success  is  inti- 
mately dependent  on  the  fact  that  they  are  entitled  to  succeed, 
because  fulfilling  some  social  or  moral  need.  Further,  it  was  shown 
that  the  chief  moral-social  requirement  centers  upon  the  recogni- 
tion of  the  infinite  worth  of  the  individual  soul  or  personality,  and 
that  to  teach  this  recognition  and  its  consequent  duties  is  the  high- 
est expression  of  that  longing  for  religion  that  is  found  through 
all  human  history. 

On  the  second  day  Professor  Hocking  took  the  lead  with  a 
presentation  of  evil  from  the  realistic  standpoint.  This  led  to 
the  suggestion  of  a  more  adequate  view,  where  evil  is  indeed  ad- 
mitted to  be  genuinely  evil,  but  where  it  is  also  more  than  merely  ex- 
istent as  a  permanent  opposition  to  good.  What  we  call  evils  can 
be  dealt  with  in  such  a  way  as  to  become  "  something  more  "  than 
merely  evil. 


84  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Professor  Creighton  of  Cornell  gave  a  presentation  of  the  phil- 
osophical meaning  of  intelligibility,  wherein  he  differentiated  phi- 
losophy from  the  explanations  current  in  the  special  sciences  and 
indicated  how  philosophical  criticism  is  not  merely  destructive, 
but  also  constructive. 

In  the  evening  Professor  Shastri  contrasted  Eastern  and  West- 
ern tendencies  in  thought  and  civilization,  and  pleaded  for  a  more 
adequate  mutual  understanding  and  a  closer  cooperation  between 
East  and  West. 

On  the  final  day  of  the  conference,  a  good  debate  was  secured 
on  the  fundamental  differences  between  the  realistic  and  the  ideal- 
istic tendencies.  Professor  Woodbridge  clearly  stated  how  this 
opposition  arose  out  of  the  emphasis  of  Descartes  on  certainty,  the 
emphasis  of  Bacon  on  power.  Professor  Hocking  maintained  the 
possibility  of  a  reconciliation,  not  by  any  superficial  or  external 
synthesis,  but  by  widening  our  interpretation  of  direct  or  immedi- 
ate experience  so  as  to  find  in  it  a  dialectical  process  seeking  the 
' '  that ' '  of  certainty,  and  an  experiential  process  seeking  the ' '  what ' ' 
of  content.  Out  of  this  suggestion  grew  a  spirited  discussion  of 
the  import  of  "intuition"  and  of  how  to  discriminate  between  a 
pseudo-problem  and  a  genuine  problem  in  philosophy.  Professor 
Creighton  summed  up  the  debate  by  claiming  that  though  there 
might  seem  to  be  an  opposition  there  was  no  real  contradiction  be- 
tween the  logical  process  of  proof  and  the  intuitional;  that,  in 
fact,  logical  proofs  became  concentrated  or  vitally  synthesized  in 
an  "intuition,"  which  was  not  an  abandonment  but  a  consumma- 
tion of  the  logical.  An  "intuition,"  then,  is  concrete  and  includes 
in  it  a  logical  factor. 

In  the  evening  a  delightful  lecture  was  given  by  Professor 
Creighton,  showing  in  a  lucid  and  interesting  way  the  contrast 
between  the  eighteenth  and  nineteenth  century  in  philosophy, 
literature  and  civilization. 

JAMES  GIBSON  HUME. 

UNIVZRSITY  or  TORONTO 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  4.  FEBRUARY  16,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  IDENTITY  OF  INSTINCT  AND  HABIT 

TWO  years  ago,  in  a  brief  paper  entitled  Are  There  Any  In- 
stinctsf  *  I  questioned  the  usefulness  of  the  conception  of 
instincts  then  prevalent  in  psychology,  pointing  out  that  while  there 
are  many  reaction  patterns  which  may  legitimately  be  called  in- 
stinctive— if  by  instinctive  we  mean  unlearned — these  reaction  pat-  • 
terns  are  not  combined  in  the  so-called  instincts  in  any  exclusive ;  - 
way,  but  that  the  same  reaction  pattern  occurs  in  several  of  the 
instincts,  and  that  in  some  of  the  instincts  practically  all  of  the 
reaction  patterns,  learned  and  unlearned,  which  the  animal  possesses, 
function  at  one  time  or  another.  The  ' '  instincts, ' '  I  concluded,  are 
teleological  groupings  of  activities,  not  psychological  groupings.  • 
They  are  teleological,  in  that  they  are  grouped  with  reference  to 
the  ends  attained  by  the  complex  activity :  not  ends  that  the  acting 
animal  holds  as  conscious  purposes,  but  ends  that  the  classifier  (the 
psychologist,  biologist,  philosopher,  or  whoever  draws  up  the  list 
of  instincts),  considers  as  attained  by  the  activity  in  question.  Lists 
of  instincts,  therefore,  represent  no  fundamental  psychological  proc- 
esses, but  merely  the  convenience  of  the  classifier:  and  any  list 
which  is  convenient  is  as  valid  as  any  other  list. 

Since  this  heretical  assault  upon  a  widely  held  doctrine  was 
delivered,  a  considerable  number  of  writers  have  taken  up  the  cudgel 
against  instincts;  and  there  seems  to  be  danger  that  denunciation 
of  instinct  will  become  as  fashionable  and  as  uncritical  as  the  accept- 
ance of  instincts  has  been  hitherto.  In  particular,  there  seems  to 
be  a  tendency  to  make  no  discrimination  between  instinctive  activity, 
instinct,  and  instincts ;  but  to  assume  that  rejecting  the  last  of  these 
disposes  of  the  others.  It  may  well  be  that  there  is  such  a  thing  as 
instinct,  namely,  action  determined  solely  by  the  environment  (stim- 
ulation pattern),  and  the  constitution  of  the  animal;  and  that  hence 
certain  actions  are  properly  called  instinctive  (without  regard  to 
what  they  accomplish  in  the  world,  of  course)  ;  although  the  "in- 
stincts" are  purely  arbitrary  groupings  of  activities.  A  recent 
author,2  in  fact,  while  rejecting  the  whole  conception  of  instinct, 
reinstates  instinctive  activities  under  the  changed  names  of  inherited 

1  Journal  of  Abnormal  Psychology,  1919,  Vol.  14,  pp.  307-311. 

2  Zing  Yang  Kuo,  ' '  Giving  up  Instincts  in  Psychology, ' '  this  JOURNAL, 
1921,  Vol.  18,  pp.  645-664. 

85 


86  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOI'JI  Y 

"action-systems,"  defining  these  in  precisely  the  same  way  in  which 
we  would  ordinarily  define  instinctive  tendencies. 

It  seems  to  me,  therefore,  necessary  to  state  a  little  more  carefully 
the  objections  to  the  old  use  of  "instincts"  in  psychology,  and  also 
to  add  the  consideration  of  certain  objections  to  the  antithesis 
usually  assumed  between  instinct  and  habit,  especially  since  these 
latter  objections  have  not  been  raised  by  any  of  the  recent  authors 
to  whom  I  refer.  In  my  present  view  concerning  this  relation  of 
instinct  and  habit,  I  am  in  part  indebted  to  Dr.  Ulrich,8  although 
I  must  confess  that  the  suggestion  comes  to  me  not  from  his  im- 
portant monograph,  but  from  personal  discussion  with  him  of 
matters  contained  therein.  I  hope  I  may  be  pardoned  if  I  repeat 
somewhat,  and  if  I  seem  to  introduce  rather  elementary  illustrations, 
for  I  now  feel  that  it  is  better  to  be  a  little  tedious  rather  than  run  the 
risk  of  not  making  my  point  understood. 

Psychologists  have  got  into  the  habit  of  contrasting  instinct  and 
intelligence.  From  that  they  have  gone  on  to  the  custom  of  speak- 
ing of  specific  instincts  as  if  they  were  really  separable  entities;4 
a  habit  that  was  wished  upon  psychologists  by  a  variety  of  men: 
philosophers,  students  of  animal  behavior,  etc.  The  machinery  of 
instincts  so  constructed  has  been  seized  on  by  several  psychologists  as 
ready-made  apparatus  for  the  construction  of  social  psychology, 
and  it  behooves  us  to  look  rather  carefully,  if  necessarily  somewhat 
hastily,  into  the  whole  question  of  instincts,  which,  of  course,  we 
have  to  separate  from  instinct  and  from  instinctive  reaction. 

We  find  in  the  animal,  human  and  infra-human,  tendencies  to 
react  in  certain  ways  to  certain  stimuli :  tendencies  to  make  certain 
definite  responses  to  certain  definite  features  of  the  environment. 
For  example:  At  a  certain  tirade  the  bell  rings,  whereupon  the  stu- 
dents in  my  room  gather  up  their  books  and  file  out  through  the 
door.  There  is  thus  demonstrated  a  tendency  to  react  in  a  particular 
way,  however  complex,  to  a  particular  stimulus  pattern,  which  in 
this  case  happens  to  be  a  relatively  simple  one.  The  reaction,  of 
course,  was  not  in  existence  during  the  time  immediately  preceding 
the  ringing  of  the  bell.  The  students,  however,  did  have  the 
tendency.  It  may  not  have  been  in  existence  during  the  whole  of  the 
hour  preceding  the  action,  but  certainly  a  number  of  minutes  before 
the  bell  rang  the  tendency  was  there,  ready  to  play  its  part  in 
bringing  about  the  action.  A  tendency,  we  may  assume,  is  a  certain 
arrangement  in  the  nervous  system;  what  Stout  and  others  have 

*"  Integration  of  Movement  in  Learning  in  the  Albino  Rat,"  Psychobio- 
logy,  1920,  VoL  2,  pp.  375-448,  455-500;  Journal  of  Comparative  Psychology, 
1921,  Vol.  1,  pp.  1-96,  155-199,  221-286. 

*  The  separation  of  intelligence  into  different  intelligences  has  not  been  so 
easily  accepted,  although  that  separation  has  been  proposed. 


THE  IDENTITY  OF  INSTINCT  AND  HABIT  87 

called  a  disposition  of  the  nervous  system:  something  which  is 
definitely  in  existence,  whether  we  describe  it  as  a  physical  or  chem- 
ical arrangement.  It  is  because  of  this  arrangement  in  the  nervous 
system  that  the  stimulus  produces  the  response.  That  the  "disposi- 
tion" exists  as  an  organic  fact,  is  further  proved  by  the  fact  that 
the  reaction,  in  a  case  such  as  we  have  described,  may  be  predicted. 

As  an  illustration  of  the  relation  of  "disposition,"  or  "tend- 
ency," to  response,  we  may  consider  an  electric  door  bell  and  its 
operation.  We  press  the  button  and  the  bell  rings;  because  there 
was  a  mechanical  arrangement  of  parts,  an  existing  "disposition" 
of  the  sort  that  made  the  response  (the  transmission  of  the  current 
and  the  ringing  of  the  bell)  possible  when  the  stimulus  (the  pressing 
of  the  button.)  was  'applied.  We  mean  by  the  "tendency"  of  an 
animal  to  react  in  a  certain  way  to  a  certain  stimulus,  nothing  more 
occult  than  the  "tendency"  of  the  bell  to  ring  when  the  button  is 
pressed. 

In  the  human  animal  some  of  these  tendencies  are  tendencies  to 
perceptual  reactions.  If  a  certain  canvas  with  certain  paint  smears 
on  it  is  presented  to  one  man,  he  perceives  a  genuine  Tintoretto; 
while  another  person  to  whom  is  presented  the  same  canvas  perceives 
only  a  dreary  daub.  Why  ?  The  two  men  have  different  perceptual 
tendencies.  There  is  a  tendency  on  the  part  of  one  man  to  react  to 
that  stimulus  in  one  way ;  and  the  other  man  has  a  tendency  to  react 
in  another  way. 

Men  have  also  divergent  emotional  tendencies.  One  man,  while 
watching  a  certain  scene  on  the  stage,  has  an  emotional  result  which 
we  might  describe  as  "interest,  with  mild  pleasure";  another  man 
reacts  with  a  sad  emotion,  akin  to  grief.  This  difference  can  be  stated 
as  due  to  a  difference  in  tendencies  which  have  previously  been  es- 
tablished, so  that  the  same  stimulus  pattern  produces  the  responses 
in  accordance  with  the  different  tendencies. 

There  are  also  thought-tendencies,  as  definite  as  the  perceptual 
and  emotional  tendencies.  If  I  mention  Plymouth  Rock  to  a  group 
of  people,  some  of  them  may  think  of  chicken-runs,  incubators, 
broilers,  and  market  reports,  while  others  may  think  of  a  stern  and 
rock-bound  coast,  where  the  breaking  waves  dash  high;  depending 
on  the  particular  tendency  existing  in  the  individual  who  is  stimu- 
lated. 

It  is  customary  to  divide  or  group  these  tendencies  under  two 
headings.  We  class  them  as  instinctive,  native,  or  inherited  on  the 
one  hand,  and  habitual,  learned,  or  acquired  on  the  other.  It  is 
further  customary  to  use  the  term  "instinct"  in  a  general  way  to 
indicate  the  existence  in  any  animal  of  native  reaction  tendencies, 
"habit"  in  a  corresponding  way  to  indicate  the  existence  of  acquired 


88  JOURNAL  OF  PJIIL080PJI  Y 

tendencies,  and  "intelligence"  to  mean  the  capacity  to  acquire  or  to 
modify  reaction  tendencies.  With  these  methods  of  speech  we  have 
no  quarrel,  and  may  accept  the  terms  as  defined. 

But  there  is  a  further  custom  of  speaking  of  certain  groups  of 
instinctive  tendencies  as  instincts.  This  usage  is  by  no  means  a 
necessary  consequence  of  those  just  described.  We  might  use  the 
term  instinct  in  a  general  way,  and  speak  in  particular  of  instinctive 
reactions,  and  yet  not  speak  of  "an  instinct"  or  "instincts"  at  all. 
The  conception  of  instincts  has  been  constructed,  however,  and  va- 
rious lists  of  "instincts"  have  been  compiled,  and  we  have  come  in 
a  rather  naive  way  to  speak  of  this  or  that  "instinct"  as  if  they  were 
separable  entities:  either  groups  of  reactions,  or  tendencies  toward 
certain  complex  reactions.  We  speak  of  the  "nesting  instinct"  of 
the  bird,  the  "instinct  of  flight,"  the  "parental  instinct,"  etc., 
through  various  lists,  these  lists  ranging  all  the  way  from  those  in- 
cluding but  two  instincts:  the  self-preservatory  and  the  reproduc- 
tive or  race-preservative;  through  the  list  of  four  which  Trotter 
considers  adequate;  to  McDougall's  list  of  twelve,  and  the  list  of 
Thorndike,  which  includes  an  indefinite  number  between  ten  and 
twenty. 

The  enumeration  of  such  lists  does  not  necessarily  involve  the 
distinction  of  "instincts"  from  simpler  tendencies;  but  in  the 
hands  of  all  those  who  have  constructed  "fundamental"  lists,  such 
a  distinction,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  is  involved.  Practically  all  of  the 
compilers  of  lists  have  refused  to  admit  to  the  group  of  "instincts" 
the  simple  reflex,  such  as  the  knee  jerk,  and  many  more  complicated 
native  reactions,  such  as  the  sucking  of  the  child. 

Criteria  are  therefore  devised  in  order  to  distinguish  instincts 
from  other  non-acquired  tendencies.  Most  of  the  classifiers  object 
to  defining  an  instinct  as  a  mere  group  of  reflexes.  McDougall 
assumes  that  consciousness  is  involved;  that  there  are  essential  con- 
scious elements  in  an  instinct;  and  does  not  accept  as  an  instinct 
an  unconscious  reaction,  however  definite.  In  a  partial  way,  McDou- 
gall makes  emotional  accompaniment  a  criterion.  In  a  certain  num- 
ber of  the  twelve  instincts,  at  least,  primary  emotions  are  assumed 
to  be  involved.  The  instinct  of  flight  involves  the  emotion  of  fear; 
repulsion  involves  disgust;  curiosity,  wonder;  pugnacity,  anger; 
self-abasement,  subjection;  self-assertion,  elation;  the  parental  in- 
stinct, tender  emotion. 

It  is  not  my  intention  to  discuss  the  various  criteria  of  instinct ; 
I  merely  mention  these  as  illustrating  the  way  in  which  psychologists 
have  taken  the  term  "instincts"  in  the  plural,  as  contrasted  with 
' '  instinctive  reaction, ' '  which  has  not  the  same  meaning. 

From  a  purely  physiological  point  of  view,  there  are  no  instincts. 


THE  IDENTITY  OF  INSTINCT  AND  HABIT  89 

There  are  groups  of  re-activities  (including  not  merely  the  end  re- 
sult, muscular  and  glandular  activities,  but  the  whole  process  in  the 
nervous  system  and  effectors),  into  which  the  minor  groups  enter 
in  varying  conditions.  In  the  activities  of  flight,  food-getting,  and 
fighting,  as  they  actually  occur,  when  the  "tendency"  passes  over 
into  action,  the  same  running  movements  may  be  present.  To  a 
large  extent  the  running  movement  in  getting  away  from  some  object 
which  is  inimical  to  the  animal,  the  running  movements  in  going 
after  food  of  an  elusive  type,  the  running  movements  in  pursuing 
an  enemy,  may  be  practically  the  same.  In  general,  the  same  minor 
complex  may  enter  now  into  this,  now  into  that  complex  which  is 
called  an  instinct,  or  the  eventuation  of  an  instinct.  Some  so-called 
instincts  are  at  times  entirely  included  in  other  instincts.  For  in- 
stance, flight,  pugnacity,  and  food  getting,  taken  just  as  groups  of 
reactivities,  may  each  occur  as  part  of  the  parental  instinct,  since 
the  parental  instinct  involves  not  merely  the  begetting  of  children, 
but  also  the  procuring  of  food  for  them,  and  the  fighting  in  their 
defense,  and  even  the  running  away  with  a  child  at  times,  if  danger 
is  too  threatening.  We  would  have,  then,  from  a  physiological  point 
of  view,  the  instinct  of  flight  and  the  instinct  of  pugnacity  as  parts 
of  the  total  complex  which  would  be  called  the  parental  instinct. 
It  seems  to  me,  moreover,  that  practically  all  of  our  activities  enter 
at  some  time  or  other  into  the  so-called  reproductive  instinct;  and 
there  are  perhaps  instances  where  the  relation  is  reversed:  where 
instinct  A  at  one  time  includes  instinct  B,  and  at  another  time  in- 
stinct B  includes  instinct  A. 

This  inclusiveness  and  overlapping  nature  of  the  so-called  in- 
stincts is  not  the  point  of  greatest  difficulty  in  classification.  The 
really  obstructive  difficulty  lies  in  the  indefinite  shading  of  one  in- 
stinct into  another.  For  example,  between  flight  and  pugnacity,  even 
when  it  is  not  a  question  of  their  being  included  in  some  other  in- 
stinct, the  lines  are  by  no  means  sharp;  for  between  the  two  there 
is  a  continuous  gradation  of  intermediate  instincts. 

If  we  attempt  to  distinguish  instincts  by  the  accompanying  emo- 
tions, we  again  find  difficulty.  Fear,  for  example,  appears  some- 
times as  self-abasement,  and  shades  by  gradations  into  wonder. 
Moreover,  fear  is  involved  in  a  number  of  the  instincts :  the  parental, 
the  gregarious,  and  sometimes  in  the  acquisitive.  So  also  the  sub- 
jective emotion  and  the  emotion  of  elation  are  both  found  at  times 
in  the  reproductive  and  parental  instincts,  and  in  the  pugnacious 
instinct.  I  should  say,  moreover,  that  there  are  indefinite  shadings 
of  emotions  between  fear  and  disgust.  The  withdrawal  from  a  situa- 
tion may  not  involve  fear  alone  or  mere  disgust,  but  may  be  marked 
by  something  between  the  two.  So  also  there  seems  to  be  indefinite 


90  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

shadings  between  fear  and  wonder,  and  fear  and  anger.  It  might  be 
said  that  these  shadings  are  mixtures;  that  we  have  in  one  case  a 
mixture  of  fear  and  anger,  and  in  another  case  a  mixture  of  fear  and 
wonder.  That  may  be  true.  But  we  have  no  clearly  marked  "ele- 
mental" fear,  or  "pure"  anger.  Fear  itself  seems  to  be  a  compl'-x 
which  varies  widely,  and  seems  to  contain  elements  which  are  also 
contained  in  anger  and  various  other  emotions,  and  at  the  present 
time  it  is  safest  to  regard  each  of  these  so-called  "primary"  emotions 
as  a  complex  of  several  elements,  some  of  which  are  common  to  several 
emotions;  and  to  regard  the  particular  emotion  present  at  any  tine 
as  dependent  upon  the  relative  strength  of  the  components.  Excite- 
ment, for  instance,  is  sometimes  present  in  fear  and  usually  in  anger. 
Again,  most  of  these  "primary"  emotions,  such  as  fear  or  anger, 
are  apparently  of  several  kinds.  The  fear  you  have  when  you  start 
running  immediately  does  not  seem  of  the  same  sort  as  the  fear 
you  have  when  you  are  struck  immobile,  and  it  is  a  question  worth 
considering  whether  these  are  the  same  fear.  To  me,  retrospection 
shows  that  they  are  not  the  same.  Again,  flight  might  occur  without 
fear,  or  at  least  without  the  kind  of  fear  which  is  usually  associated 
with  flight.  I  have  found  myself  running,  after  a  motor  car  has 
honked  beside  me  on  a  street  crossing,  and  yet  have  not  found  the 
inner  content  which  I  call  fear.  The  emotion  in  such  cases  I  should 
call  "startle"  or  "being  startled  ";  but  not  "fear." 

I  think  the  assumption  that  there  is  a  very  simple  or  constant 
thing  to  be  called  fear,  another  to  be  called  anger,  and  so  on,  is 
certainly  a  dangerous  one.  If  there  are  such  constant  things,  the 
evidence  so  far  does  not  demonstrate  it.  I  can  not  see  at  the  present 
time  any  great  hope  for  the  evolution  of  a  list  of  "instincts"  on  the 
basis  of  the  emotions. 

If  we  should  now  attempt  to  distinguish  reaction-tendencies  on 
the  basis  of  desire,  or  the  purpose  of  the  reacting  animal  (not  the 
purpose  of  the  classifiers),  we  might  be  on  a  better  foundation.  I 
think,  myself,  there  is  a  distinct  possibility  there,  and  have  been 
working  on  this  line  for  several  years.  I  should  say,  however,  that 
in  this  we  are  getting  away  from  the  instinct  basis  altogether:  that 
the  classification  of  activities  in  accordance  with  their  furtherance  of 
desires  is  a  very  different  problem  from  that  in  which  McDougall, 
Watson,  and  Trotter  have  been  interested.  Such  a  system  of  distinc- 
tion would  depend,  not  on  a  primary  classification  of  activity  groups, 
but  on  a  working  out  of  the  total  activities  of  the  organism  now  in 
this  way,  and  now  in  that,  from  a  strictly  psychological  point  of  view. 

The  actual  basis  of  all  the  suggested  lists  of  instincts  is  in  the 
purposes  of  the  classifier,  not  in  the  purpose  of  the  reacting  animal. 
All  the  unlearned  activities  of  the  animal  which  the  classifier  views 


THE  IDENTITY  OF  INSTINCT  AND  HABIT  91 

as  contributing  to  the  obtaining  of  food  are  considered  by  him  as 
the  "feeding  instinct."  All  of  those  which,  from  the  point  of  view 
of  the  classifier,  culminate  in  the  perpetuation  of  the  species,  are 
considered  the  "reproductive  instinct."  Any  end  or  purpose  which 
the  classifier  considers  as  important  enough  to  set  over  against  other 
ends  is  the  point  of  departure  for  the  erection  of  "an  instinct." 
This  is  the  teleological  method,  not  the  psychological.  Now,  from 
such  a  point  of  view,  the  classifier  may  erect  as  many  instincts  as 
will  accomplish  his  own  purposes.  There  is  no  reason  for  objecting 
to  a  "mathematical  instinct,"  unless  you  do  so  on  the  ground  of 
universality.  There  are  results  in  the  world  which  involve  getting 
together  the  mathematical  relationship  of  things,  and  the  tendency 
to  work  towards  these  results  is  native  to  some  people,  if  not  to  all. 
The  "musical  instinct,"  the  "religious  instinct,"  and  many  others, 
are  also  widely  distributed.  There  certainly  is  such  a  thing  as  re- 
ligion and  activities  which  produce  certain  results  which  are  desig- 
nated as  religious,  and  if  we  judge  by  history  and  by  contemporary 
events,  tendencies  toward  these  sorts  of  activities  are  universal, 
and  have  a  native  basis  in  the  constitution  of  human  organisms. 
There  is  also  a  tendency  in  the  human  animal  to  construct  a  political 
system. 

The  popular  writers  who  construct  any  instincts  they  please  are 
quite  in  accord  with  the  general  system  of  instinct  classification. 
In  using  the  term  "an  instinct,"  you  must  conceive  of  a  definite 
and  describable  type  of  result  which  may  be  attained  by  activities 
of  various  sorts,  and  assume  that  some  of  these  activities  are  un- 
learned. Any  system  of  classification  which  is  adequate  for  your 
purpose  is  quite  valid.  A  list  of  instincts  is  a  good  deal  like  a 
filing  system:  you  may  file  all  your  documents  under  the  letter  of 
the  alphabet  with  which  the  name  of  the  writer  begins,  or  you  may 
file  by  subjects,  or  by  dates.  One  system  is  useful  in  one  business, 
another  is  more  useful  in  another  business.  But  an  industry  can  not 
be  founded  on  a  filing  system;  neither  can  a  system  of  social  psy- 
chology be  founded  on  a  classification  of  instincts. 

But  after  all,  this  difficulty  with  instincts  is  only  a  minor  one. 
While  I  am  glad  to  see  that  many  persons  interested  in  social  psy- 
chology are  beginning  to  doubt  the  usefulness  of  specific  instincts 
as  bases  for  work,  I  think  there  is  a  still  graver  difficulty  in  the 
whole  question  of  instinct  and  instinctive  reactions,  a  difficulty 
which  rather  seriously  concerns  not  only  the  foundations  of  certain 
types  of  social  psychology,  but  also  some  of  our  conceptions  of  educa- 
tion and  eugenics. 

We  have  been  so  far  assuming  that  there  is  a  fundamental  differ- 
ence, in  human  and  other  animals,  between  instinctive  and  acquired 


92  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

reactions.  Instinctive  reactions  we  have  tentatively  supposed  to  be 
native  tenileiieies  to  respond  to  stimuli  in  specific  ways;  and  acquired 
reactions  are  supposed  to  be  those  tendencies  which  are  derived 
from  previous  reactions  and  innate  dispositions  together.  Starting 
with  a  tendency  to  some  definite  reaction  to  a  definite  stimulus,  va- 
rious other  reactions  modify  this  tendency  and  eventually  an  acquired 
tendency,  distinjruishably  different  from  the  original  tendency,  arises. 

This  conception  of  the  two  classes  of  reactions,  easily  accepted  in 
the  past,  is  indeed  questionable.  In  the  life  of  the  higher  animal, 
there  are  seldom,  if  ever,  simple  reactions  to  simple  stimuli.  The 
actual  occurrences  are  complex  stimulus  patterns  and  complex  reac- 
tions. We  find  some  reactions,  such  as  the  knee-jerk,  in  which  both 
stimulus  and  reaction  are  relatively  simple;  and  some,  such  as  the 
infant's  sucking  reaction,  in  which  the  stimulus  seems  simple,  al- 
though the  reaction  is  complex.  But  in  the  main,  the  actual  adjust- 
ments of  the  organism  to  its  environment  are  complex  in  both  re- 
spects, and  even  the  sucking  reaction  involves  more  of  a  stimulus 
pattern  than  we  ordinarily  suppose. 

The  stimulus  pattern  of  an  instinctive  reaction,  as  such  reactions 
are  usually  conceived,  is  assumed  to  be  a  purely  spatial  one :  that  is, 
not  temporal  also.  In  such  a  reaction,  only  the  stimuli  of  the  move- 
ment are  effective.  In  the  instinctive  flying  of  a  bird,  assuming  such 
to  occur,  the  visual,  tactual,  kinesthetic,  and  perhaps  auditory  stimuli 
of  the  moment  are  assumed  to  be  effective :  the  stimuli  of  preceding 
minutes,  hours,  and  days,  and  the  reactions  evoked  thereby,  are  as- 
sumed to  be  negligible.  If  these  preceding  stimuli  and  reactions  do 
contribute  to,  or  modify,  the  reaction,  then  the  reaction  is  in  so  far 
not  instinctive,  but  learned. 

The  characteristic  of  the  learned  reaction  is  just  the  temporal 
stimulus  pattern.  In  playing  billiards,  for  example,  the  movements 
of  the  arm  and  body  are  the  results  not  of  the  stimulus  of  the  moment 
alone,  but  are  the  results  of  a  stimulus  pattern  which  extends  over  a 
long  period  of  time,  perhaps  months  or  years. 

But  both  of  these  reactions,  the  acquired  reaction  and  the  so- 
called  instinctive  one,  are  equally  "native."  Suppose  that  a  child 
is  given  a  small  piece  of  sandpaper  at  an  early  age,  and  that  he  puts 
that  in  his  mouth,  and  subsequently  cries.  If  the  piece  of  sandpaper 
is  given  him  repeatedly,  the  child  eventually  will  react  in  a  quite 
different  way.  Instead  of  grabbing  the  sandpaper,  he  will  turn  his 
head  away  and  cry,  and  go  through  other  reactions  which  express  his 
intention  of  not  putting  the  sandpaper  in  his  mouth.  The  sand- 
paper in  this  case  is  the  stimulus.  At  the  first  presentation,  when 
the  child  put  it  in  his  mouth,  we  have  a  so-called  instinctive  reaction. 
At  the  last  presentation,  when  he  does  not  put  it  in  his  mouth  but 


THE  IDENTITY  OF  INSTINCT  AND  HABIT  93 

does  something  else,  we  have  a  so-called  acquired  reaction.  At  the 
first  time,  it  is  assumed  by  current  theory,  the  child 's  nervous  system 
was  so  disposed  that  that  particular  stimulus,  regardless  of  other 
stimuli  preceding  it,  caused  that  particular  reaction ;  and  at  the  last 
time  the  child's  nervous  system  was  so  constituted  by  heredity 
and  the  results  of  repeated  stimulation,  that  the  same  stimulation 
at  that  particular  time  produced  a  different  reaction.  In  the  one 
case,  there  is  a  spatial,  in  the  other  a  temporal,  pattern.  But  after  all, 
are  not  the  two  cases  of  the  same  kind,  and  equally  "instinctive"  ? 
Is  the  difference  between  a  temporal  pattern  and  a  spatial  pattern 
great  enough  to  be  made  so  important,  even  if  we  should  admit  the 
possibility  of  a  purely  temporal  pattern?  The  general  statement 
of  the  reaction  tendency  in  the  two  cases  is  much  the  same.  If  it 
is  true  that  the  child 's  organism,  at  the  first  trial,  is  so  constituted 
by  heredity  that  the  first  stimulation  produces  the  first  reaction  (put- 
ting the  sandpaper  in  the  mouth),  is  it  not  equally  true  that  his 
organism  is  at  that  moment  so  constituted  that  another  stimulus 
(the  repeated  presentation  of  the  sandpaper)  will  produce  another 
reaction  (avoiding  the  sandpaper)  ?  Are  not  both  reactions  equally 
"instinctive"  ?  Is  not  the  reaction  to  a  temporal  stimulus  pattern 
just  as  "native"  as  the  reaction  to  a  stimulus  pattern  merely  spa- 
tially conditioned? 

But,  the  reader  may  say,  admitting  that  all  reactions  are  equally 
"instinctive,"  both  are  not  equally  "acquired."  Admitting  that 
the  second  reaction  is  as  fully  native  as  the  first,  is  there  not  some- 
thing more  in  the  second,  or  in  the  condition  of  the  second  ?  Even 
this  we  may  very  seriously  deny.  After  all,  there  is  no  such  thing 
as  a  "merely  spatial"  pattern:  all  patterns  are  temporal,  and  all 
reactions  equally  "acquired." 

Let  us  consider  such  a  complex  reaction  system  as  the  nest-build- 
ing of  the  robin.  How  could  this  occur  without  preceding  stimuli 
and  reactions  involved  in  the  processes  of  feeding,  flying,  etc.  ?  Sup- 
pose the  bird  had  not  gone  through  this  preceding  reaction  series. 
Can  we  assume  that  his  nervous  system  could  have  developed  to  the 
point  where  the  nest-building  tendency  would  appear?  We  can 
not.  In  other  words,  a  temporal  pattern  extending  far  back  of  the 
beginning  of  the  nest-building,  is  involved ;  and  our  basis  for  distin- 
guishing between  this  sort  of  reaction  and  habit  completely  disap- 
pears. 

Suppose  we  consider  some  of  the  less  complex  reactions:  the 
sucking  reaction  of  the  child,  for  example.  Suppose  the  child  had 
not  first  been  stimulated  by  cold  air,  and  pressure,  in  such  a  way 
as  to  produce  the  crying  reaction:  could  the  sucking  reaction  have 
been  evoked  later?  Here,  again,  we  can  not  get  away  from  the  effects 


94  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  preceding  stimuli.  In  this  case  it  might  be  said  that  we  are 
not  dealing  with  a  specific  effect  on  the  nervous  system  in  the  way 
of  modification,  but  with  the  preservation  of  the  integrity  of  the 
nervous  system.  But  this  is  a  distinction  without  a  valid  difference. 
We  are  concerned  with  a  condition  in  the  nervous  system  which  makes 
a  certain  specific  reaction  possible,  and  any  other  stimuli  which 
are  essential  to  putting  the  nervous  system  in  such  condition,  or 
to  maintaining  it  in  such  condition,  through  the  reaction  evoked, 
must  be  considered  as  a  part  of  the  stimulus  pattern.  Our  knowledge 
of  the  nervous  system  does  not  permit  us  to  go  beyond  this  point. 
At  the  present  time,  I  can  see  no  way  of  distinguishing  usefully 
between  instinct  and  habit.  All  reactions  are  definite  responses  to 
definite  stimulus  patterns,  and  the  exact  character  of  the  response 
is  determined  in  every  case  by  the  inherited  constitution  of  the 
organism  and  the  stimulus  pattern.  All  reactions  are  instinctive: 
all  are  acquired.  If  we  consider  instinct,  we  find  it  to  be  the  form 
and  method  of  habit-formation :  if  we  consider  habit,  we  find  it  to  be 
the  way  in  which  instinct  exhibits  itself.  Practically,  we  use  the 
term  instinctive  reaction  to  designate  any  reaction  whose  antecedents 
we  do  not  care,  at  the  time,  to  inquire  into ;  by  acquired  reaction,  on 
the  other  hand,  we  mean  those  reactions  for  whose  antecedents  we 
intend  to  give  some  account.  But  let  us  beware  of  founding  a  psy- 
chology, social,  general,  or  individual,  on  such  a  distinction. 

KNIGHT  DUNLAP. 
JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY. 


MUST  WE  GIVE  UP  INSTINCTS  IN  PSYCHOLOGY? 

IN  a  recent  number  of  this  JOURNAL  (Vol.  XVIII,  No.  24)  there  ap- 
peared an  article  entitled  ' '  Giving  Up  Instincts  in  Psychology ' ' 
by  Mr.  Zing  Yang  Kuo,  of  the  University  of  California,  in  which 
the  writer  argued  not  only  that  instincts  have  been  overworked  as 
explanatory  concepts  in  psychology,  but  that,  as  a  matter  of  fact, 
there  are  no  such  things  as  instincts  in  human  nature.  This  point 
of  view  and  many  of  the  considerations  urged  in  behalf  of  it  are 
interesting  and  stimulating.  There  are  several  points,  however,  at 
which  the  writer's  argument  appears  to  me  to  be  loose  and  open  to 
attack.  For  example,  emphasis  is  laid  on  the  fact  that  "there  is  no 
general  agreement  among  the  students  of  instincts  as  to  the  number 
and  kinds  of  instincts. ' '  That  there  is  such  a  lack  of  general  agree- 
ment among  students  of  instincts  no  one  would  deny.  But  this  does 
not  imply  the  non-existence  of  instincts;  it  merely  reflects  the  lack 
of  scientific  accuracy  and  completeness  in  this  field  of  investigation. 


MUST  WE  GIVE  UP  INSTINCTS?  95 

This  lack  of  accuracy  and  completeness  in  enumerating  and  classify- 
ing the  instincts  is  doubtless  due  in  part  to  the  relatively  short 
period  of  time  that  instincts  have  been  made  the  objects  of  scientific 
study.  It  may  also  be  due  to  the  specialized  and  partial  points  of 
view  from  which  instincts  have  been  considered.  Students  in  this 
field  have  for  the  most  part  been  concerned  with  instinctive  tenden- 
cies as  these  are  implicated  in  various  social  processes  and  institu- 
tions. It  was  inevitable,  because  of  this  circumstance,  that  confusion 
and  differences  should  arise  with  reference  to  the  number  and  kinds 
of  instincts.  But  this  confusion  and  these  differences  may  be  ex- 
pected to  gradually  pass  away  as  methods  of  study  become  more 
refined  and  the  points  of  view  from  which  investigations  are  made 
become  more  objective. 

Again,  the  writer  attempts  to  establish  an  analogy  between  the 
theory  of  instinct  as  implying  a  prwri  relation  of  the  organism 
to  the  environment  and  the  theory  of  innate  ideas ;  and  argues  that 
one  is  as  objectionable  as  the  other.  He  says:  "To  assume  any 
inborn  tendency  is  to  assume  a  priori  relation  between  the  organism 
and  stimulating  objects;  for  every  behavior  is  an  interaction  between 
the  organism  and  its  surrounding  objects.  Such  an  assumption  is 
no  less  objectionable  than  the  theory  of  innate  ideas.  As  a  matter  of 
fact  both  the  theory  of  instinct  and  that  of  innate  ideas  are  based  on 
the  same  conception ;  namely,  the  conception  of  a  priori  relation  of 
the  organism  to  external  objects"  (p.  648).  Now  if  we  are  war- 
ranted in  speaking  of  an  inborn  tendency  as  implying  a  priori  rela- 
tion between  organism  and  environment  in  an  objectionable  sense, 
a  very  large  part  of  the  structural  and  functional  equipment  of  the 
organism  must  be  regarded  as  involving  the  same  implication.  Re- 
lations between  the  organism  and  the  environment  in  the  way  of 
behavior  depend  on  and  presuppose  the  skeletal  system,  vital  organs, 
receptors  and  limbs  quite  as  much  as  they  depend  on  and  presuppose 
tendencies  to  action,  whether  innate  or  acquired.  There  is  a  sense  of 
course  in  which  these  relations  may  be  said  to  be  a  priori,  namely 
in  the  sense  that  the  structures  and  functions  which  they  bring  into 
operation  are  fitted  in  advance  of  experience  to  interact  with  the 
environment  in  significant  ways.  But  there  is  nothing  mysterious 
or  miraculous  about  a  priori  capacities  in  this  sense.  They  represent 
the  selective  influence  of  the  environment  on  the  life  stream  from 
which  the  organism  springs.  And  whatever  there  is  of  a  priori 
character  about  an  inborn  tendency,  i.e.,  an  instinct,  is  to  be  ac- 
counted for  in  the  same  way.  Innate  ideas,  however,  when  they 
have  been  ascribed  to  the  mind,  have  not  been  thought  of  as  being 
a  priori  in  this  sense.  Rather  they  have  been  referred  to  some  tran- 
scendental source  which  has  been  set  over  against  and  contrasted 


96  JOURNAL  OF  PHlLOSOl'll  V 

with  the  empirical  and  biological  agencies  conditioning  our  nat 
Mr.  Kuo's  contention  that  "hotli  the  theory  of  instinct  and  that  of 
innate  ideas  are  based  on  the  same  conception;  namely,  that  of 
(i  }>rinri  relation  of  the  organism  to  external  objects,"  overlooks  the 
fact  that  the  a  priori  character  of  the  relation  in  the  two  cases  is 
entirely  different. 

Furthermore,  it  would  seem  that  while  Mr.  Kuo  rejects  the  notion 
of  an  "inborn  tendency"  because  it  implies  a  priori  relation  of  the 
organism  to  the  environment,  he  neverthless  is  forced  to  presuppose 
this  conception  in  accounting  for  the  development  of  behavior.  More 
specifically,  it  is  admitted  that  "the  human  infant  is  endowed  with 
a  great  number  of  units  of  reaction"  (p.  658) ;  and  by  "units  of 
reaction"  is  meant  the  "elementary  acts  out  of  which  various  co- 
ordinated activities  of  later  life  are  organized"  (p.  658).  Now 
these  "units  of  reaction"  or  "elementary  acts"  must  be  presumed 
to  involve  innate  neural  tracts  making  possible  just  these  responses 
and  no  others,  however  simple  and  undifferentiated  in  character  they 
may  be.  We  may  call  these  responses  "spontaneous"  or  "random"; 
but  these  are  relative  terms.  They  do  not  imply  that  we  regard  the 
responses  in  question  as  being  accidental  or  unconditioned.  \Ve  call 
such  responses  spontaneous  or  random  because  they  do  not  seem 
to  us  to  fall  into  any  purposive  system.  And  yet,  they  serve  this 
purpose  at  least :  they  are  the  stuff  out  of  which,  as  Mr.  Kuo  says, 
"the  coordinated  activities  of  later  life  are  organized."  At  any  rate, 
these  "units  of  reaction"  or  "elementary  acts"  with  which  the  in- 
dividual is  endowed  at  birth  presuppose  neural  tracts  which  can 
only  be  described  as  "inborn  tendencies"  i.e.,  tendencies  to  perform 
certain  definite  responses  and  no  others;  and  as  such  they  imply 
a  priori  relation  between  organism  and  environment  of  the  same 
character  which  Mr.  Kuo  rejects  in  the  case  of  instincts.  Indeed, 
these  "inborn  tendencies"  which  become  overt  actions  upon  the 
presentation  of  the  appropriate  stimuli,  are  called,  in  another  con- 
nection, "non-specific  instincts"  (p.  658).  Whatever  we  may  call 
them,  they  differ  from  instincts,  as  commonly  understood,  not  in  the 
fact  that  they  are  irrelevant  to  environmental  conditions  as  repre- 
sented by  the  stimuli  which  excite  them,  whereas  instincts  involve 
inborn  tendencies  which  are  relevant  to  the  environment;  but  in 
the  fact  that  they  are  not  organized  into  systems  serving  specific 
biological  ends. 

But  the  argument  at  another  point  seems  to  me  to  imply  the 
existence  of  instincts  in  this  more  specific  and  purposive  sense.  I 
have  in  mind  the  interpretation  given  Spaulding's  experiment  on 
the  flight  of  birds.  "That  the  birds  could  fly  without  previous  edu- 
cation," says  Mr.  Kuo  "was  rather  due  to  the  maturity  of  reaction 


MUST  WE  GIVE  UP  INSTINCTS?  97 

system.  .  .  .  Given  a  mature  reaction  system  and  given  an  environ- 
mental demand,  a  definite  reaction  can  fairly  be  predicted"  (p.  653). 
Now  it  is  important  to  know  just  what  the  writer  means  to  include 
within  such  a  "reaction  system"  which  is  capable  in  advance  of  all 
education,  when  properly  stimulated,  of  executing  an  intricate  and 
significant  action  such  as  full-fledged  flight.  He  speaks  of  the  partic- 
ular "reaction  system"  utilized  in  the  flight  of  Spaulding's  birds 
as  including  "wings  and  other  flying  mechanisms"  (p.  653).  What 
are  these  other  "flying  mechanisms"  ?  Do  they  not  include  nerve 
centers  and  nerve  connections  ?  And  if  so,  must  these  not  be  thought 
of  as  forming  and  ripening  in  advance  of  experiences  having  to  do 
with  flight?  To  account  for  their  tendency  and  ability,  and  the 
tendency  and  ability  of  other  mechanisms  involved,  to  execute  ade- 
quate flying  movements  by  reference  to  their  maturity  is  beside  the 
mark;  the  question  is,  did  this  state  of  maturity  result  from  former 
efforts  to  fly?  If  not  (as  in  the  case  of  Spaulding's  experiment),  it 
must  have  developed  out  of  conditions  which  were  present  in  the 
organism  at  birth;  in  which  case,  I  do  not  see  that  the  notion  of 
instinct  can  be  excluded  from  a  scientific  interpretation  of  the  facts. 
It  is  true,  of  course,  that  any  action,  instinctive  or  acquired,  is 
conditioned  by  the  presentation  of  an  appropriate  stimulus.  But  the 
stimulus  is  not  the  cause  of  the  action ;  there  is  no  mechanical  equiva- 
lence between  the  stimulus  and  the  response  that  we  are  able  to  make 
out.  It  is  only  a  cue  for  the  execution  of  movements  provided  for 
in  some  ' '  reaction  system. ' '  And  given  the  stimulus  and  the  ' '  reac- 
tion system"  we  can  predict  the  response  to  be  expected  only  if  we 
have  in  mind  the  purpose  served  by  such  mechanisms  as  are  under 
consideration.  We  can  be  certain,  for  example,  that  birds  kept  in 
small  boxes  until  their  wings  and  other  flying  mechanisms  have 
matured  will  fly  when  there  is  an  environmental  demand  for  this 
action,  because  we  know  in  advance  that  wings  and  the  mechanisms 
connected  therewith  are  developed  for  flying.  Without  this  advance 
information,  turning  the  birds  loose  in  the  air  with  nothing  to  support 
them  might,  for  all  we  could  tell,  result  in  any  other  action  as  well 
as  in  flight.  And  so  it  is  in  the  case  of  any  combination  of  stimulus 
and  "reaction  system"  :  our  ability  to  predict  a  definite  response 
always  presupposes  an  insight  into  the  functional  character  of  the  re- 
lationship involved.  Mere  knowledge  of  the  stimulus  as  a  brute  fact 
and  of  the  reaction  mechanisms  as  so  many  structural  entities  is  not 
sufficient.  This  means  that  the  primary  condition  of  significant 
activity,  as  well  as  of  spontaneous  or  random  movement,  is  internal 
rather  than  external.  Whether  we  think  of  this  condition  in  terms 
of  McDougall's  "drives"  or  "springs  to  action"  or  in  terms  of  Mr. 
Kuo's  "reaction  systems,"  the  emphasis  falls  on  the  neural  struc- 


98  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

tures  of  the  organism  rather  than  on  environmental  factors.  And 
however  complex  this  inner  tendency  to  action  is,  and  however  much 
of  its  complexity  and  significance  it  may  owe,  at  any  moment  of  its 
history,  to  the  modifying  influences  of  education  or  training,  it 
presupposes  a  minimum  core  or  foundation  in  the  inherited  struc- 
tures of  the  organism  without  which  it  could  not  have  had  a  begin- 
ning. The  minimum  core  or  foundation  thus  presupposed,  in  so  far 
as  it  is  inborn,  and  in  so  far  as  it  makes  possible  significant  inter- 
actions with  the  environment,  is,  it  seems  to  me,  on  the  basis  of  Mr. 
Kuo's  own  argument,  deserving  of  the  name  "instinct." 

J.  R.  QEIGER. 
COLLEGE  or  WILLIAM  AND  MART. 


THE  MODIFICATION  OF  INSTINCT 

IN  an  article  on  "The  Modification  of  Instinct  from  the  Standpoint 
of  Social  Psychology,"  published  in  the  Psychological  Review, 
volume  27,  1920,  pp.  247-69,  I  took  the  position  that  instinct  could 
be  modified  by  habits  formed  prior  to  the  instinct's  appearance.  As 
a  partial  support  for  this  view,  I  cited  the  following  observation 
made  by  C.  O.  Whitman  upon  pigeons : 

If  a  bird  of  one  species  is  batched  and  reared  by  a  wholly  different  species, 
it  is  very  apt  when  fully  grown  to  prefer  to  mate  with  the  species  under  which 
it  has  been  reared.  For  example,  a  male  passenger-pigeon  that  was  reared  with 
ring-doves  and  had  remained  with  that  species  was  ever  ready,  when  fully  grown, 
to  mate  with  any  ring-dove,  but  could  never  be  induced  to  mate  with  one  of  his  own 
species.  I  kept  him  away  from  ring-doves  a  whole  season,  in  order  to  see  what 
could  be  accomplished  in  the  way  of  getting  him  mated  finally  with  his  own 
species,  but  he  would  never  make  any  advances  to  the  females,  and  whenever  a 
ring-dove  was  seen  or  heard  in  the  yard  he  was  at  once  attentive. 

Professor  H.  A.  Carr,  in  editing  the  Whitman  manuscript,  also 
directed  attention  to  the  principle  involved.  Since  the  publication 
of  my  paper,  this  interpretation  has  been  questioned  first  by  Pro- 
fessor James  Leuba  in  private  correspondence  and  last  by  Mr. 
Zing  Yang  Kuo,  in  a  most  interesting  paper  upon  "Giving  up  In- 
stincts in  Psychology,"  this  JOURNAL,  Volume  18,  1921,  pp.  656-7. 
The  criticism  urged  is  that  the  behavior  of  the  pigeons  so  modified 
was  not  an  instinct  but  a  habit.  The  passenger-pigeons'  choices  of 
mates  from  their  own  species  are  themselves,  so  it  is  said,  the  result 
of  training  and  association  and  are  not  innate.  Therefore,  so  the 
conclusion  runs,  we  do  not  have  the  modification  of  an  instinct, 
but  merely  the  supplanting  of  one  habit  by  another. 

The  proper  understanding  of  much  human  and  animal  behavior 
depends  to  such  an  extent  upon  the  principle  here  involved  that 
I  wish  to  suggest  the  answer  to  the  problem  as  I  see  it : 


THE  MODIFICATION  OF  INSTINCT  99 

For  the  principle  concerned,  it  makes  no  difference  whether  the 
specific  choice  of  mates  by  normally  reared  passenger-pigeons  is 
chiefly  inherited  or  acquired.  The  modification  brought  about  is 
of  the  same  general  type  as  that  found  in  the  conditioned  reflex, 
save  for  the  temporal  location  of  the  modifying  influences.  Whit- 
man's observation  gives  us  a  case  which  is  scientifically  described 
and  convenient  to  use,  but  illustrations  might  be  drawn  as  well 
from  man's  sex  choices,  from  the  field  of  sex  education,  and  else- 
where. The  sex  instinct  consists  of  those  motor  and  glandular  activi- 
ties whose  occurrence  is  due  to  an  inherited  synaptic  connection 
giving  certain  sensory  impulses  ready  access  to  the  necessary  final 
common  paths.  The  instinct  is  certain  behavior  set  up  in  muscles 
and  glands.  It  is  not  a  stimulus,  nor  yet  an  inherited  synaptic  con- 
nection, but  is  aroused  by  the  former  and  controlled  by  the  latter. 
Considered  most  accurately  the  instinct  is  not  modified  unless  effec- 
tor activities  are  changed.  We  are  considering,  however,  as  others 
have  considered,  the  modification  of  the  total  inherited  stimulus- 
response  situation.  The  immediate  problem  is  whether  or  not  habit- 
ual associations  formed  prior  to  the  appearance  of  the  instinct  have 
set  certain  stimuli  as  the  ones  which  will  be  effective  in  arousing  the 
instinct. 

The  detailed  stimuli  arousing  sex  behavior  are  unknown.  In 
general,  however,  two  classes  of  stimuli  are  involved :  visceral  sensory 
impulses  corresponding  to  appetite,  or  desire,  on  the  conscious  side ; 
and  somatic  sensory  impulses  aroused  by  the  external  object  or  by 
the  symbol  which  represents  it.  It  is  probable  that  in  many  animals 
there  is  not  a  high  degree  of  specificity  on  the  somatic  sensory  side 
and  that  these  factors  are  supplied  to  a  high  degree  by  the  experience 
of  the  individual.  However,  the  chance  selection  of  somatic  avenues 
seems  to  be  weighted  in  favor  of  cutaneous,  olfactory  and  possibly 
visual  stimulation,  i.e.,  the  somatic  avenues  do  not  seem  to  be  equally 
open.  On  the  visceral  sensory  side  there  seems  to  be  an  undoubted 
native  connection  between  internal  secretions  and  the  appearance 
of  sex  responses  in  the  somatic  and  visceral  effectors  (just  as  there 
is  a  connection  between  stomach  contractions  and  feeding  activities 
in  normal  animals).  Exercise  seems  able  only  to  vary  this  visceral 
sensory  factor  and  so  affect  the  intensity  of  the  appetite.  Whether 
or  not  this  is  actually  the  case,  I  do  not  know.  (A  diagram  indicat- 
ing the  coexistence  of  the  two  types  of  sensory  avenues  is  presented 
on  page  253  of  my  paper  above  cited.) 

What  Whitman's  observations  show  is  that  prior  to  the  appear- 
ance of  that  typical  form  of  response  known  as  sex  behavior  the 
associations  established  within  the  lifetime  of  the  pigeon  have 
changed  the  stimuli  which  will  later  help  in  eliciting  tlir  rrr-ponse  by 


100  JOURNAL  OF 

varying  the  synaptic  connections  on  the  somatic  sensory  side  of  the 
arc.  The  contrast  between  mating  with  members  of  the  same  species 
in  the  one  case  and  with  members  of  another  species  in  the  other 
case  gives  the  essential  fact.  In  ncitlu-r  instance  need  the  stimulus 
be  connected  with  the  response  through  synapses  set  by  heredity 
in  order  that  the  modification  of  instinctive  behavior  conform  to 
the  principle  stated.  If  experiment  should  show  that  there  is  no 
somatic  afferent  connection  set  by  heredity  to  arouse  the  mating 
response,  the  stimulus-response  fact  would  of  course  be  different 
from  what  I  am  inclined  to  assume,  viz.,  that  along  with  the  inherited 
motor  grouping  goes  a  more  or  less  definite  nervous  organization 
favoring  certain  somatic  stimuli.  But  such  results,  if  secured,  would 
only  further  confirm  the  fact  that  associations  formed  prior  to  the 
appearance  of  the  instinct  may  modify  it  (either  on  the  motor  or 
on  the  sensory  side)  when  it  does  appear.  In  the  food-getting  in- 
stinct in  chicks  one  has  an  instinct  similar  to  the  sex  instinct  in 
that  the  sensory  components  of  each  include  both  somatic  and  vis- 
ceral factors  and  in  that  the  somatic  stimuli  are  less  definite  than 
they  later  become.  The  chick  pecks  at  first  in  response  to  visual 
stimulation  from  any  small  object  or  in  response  to  an  overpowering 
appetite  in  the  absence  of  the  proper  external  stimulus.  With  prac- 
tise the  somatic  stimuli  become  confined  largely  to  food  objects.  The 
significant  difference  between  the  food-getting  and  the  mate-getting 
responses  is  that  one  appears  shortly  after  birth  and  the  other  much 
later.  The  food-getting  instinct  therefore  offers  little  opportunity 
for  modification  by  experience  either  on  the  sensory  or  on  the  motor 
side  prior  to  its  appearance. 

I  do  not  regard  it  as  the  function  of  this  paper  to  discuss  the 
question  of  whether  or  not  instincts  do  exist.  The  psychologists 
who  are  questioning  the  existence  of  inherited  forms  of  response  may 
do  the  science  a  service  in  forcing  a  more  definite  use  of  terms,  but 
so  far  the  prospects  of  attaining  their  avowed  goal  do  not  seem 
encouraging.  To  disprove  the  existence  of  instincts,  one  must  either 
disprove  the  existence  of  reflexes  or  prove  that  there  is  a  significant 
difference  in  kind  between  the  behavior  termed  instinct  and  that 
termed  reflex.  Mr.  Kuo  discounts  the  idea  of  the  existence  of  in- 
stincts  partly  because  the  behavior  in  question  involves  the  coordi- 
nation of  simpler  responses,  and  coordination  he  holds  to  be  the 
result  of  habit.  However,  physiological  work  indicates  that  even 
the  simplest  reflexes  are  coordinated  activities.  The  author  also 
disputes  the  existence  of  delayed  instincts,  inherited  forms  of  be- 
havior appearing  at  varying  intervals  after  birth.  Various  angles 
of  this  question  have  been  long  discussed,  but  I  cite  in  opposition 
to  Mr.  Kuo's  view  only  Lloyd  Morgan's  somewhat  theoretical  dis- 


BOOK  REVIEWS  101 

cussion  of  the  moorhen's  first  dive  and  Yerkes's  and  Blooinfield's 
experimental  observations  on  the  behavior  of  kittens  in  killing  mice. 
In  order  to  disprove  the  existence  of  delayed  instincts,  it  is  not 
sufficient  to  indicate  that  elements  of  the  response  have  been  exer- 
cised before.  It  is  necessary  to  account  for  the  somewhat  sudden 
grouping  of  the  elements  into  a  significantly  new  response  under 
conditions  where  the  influence  of  habit  formation  is  experimentally 
controlled  and  negligible. 

The  opponents  of  instinct  will  also  have  a  very  considerable 
difficulty  in  handling  such  data,  meager  though  it  is,  as  that  pre- 
sented by  Yerkes  on  the  inheritance  of  savageness  and  wildness  in 
rats  and  by  Whitman  on  the  hybridization  of  pigeon  behavior. 

There  are  other  interesting — tout  I  think  seriously  mistaken — 
points  both  in  Mr.  Kuo's  paper  and  in  other  recent  papers  couched 
in  a  similar  vein.  My  purpose,  however,  is  merely  to  remove  the 
misapprehension  which  has  come  to  my  notice  with  reference  to  an 
earlier  proposition,  viz.,  that  associations  formed  prior  to  the  appear- 
ance of  an  instinct  may  modify  the  instinct  when  it  appears. 

WALTER  S.  HUNTER. 

THE  UNIVERSITY  OF  KANSAS. 


Mysticism,  Freudianism  and  Scientific  Psychology.    KNIGHT  DUN- 
LAP.     St.  Louis:  C.  V.  Mosby  Company,  1920.     Pp.  173. 

There  are  two  main  points  of  interest  in  this  stimulating  essay : 
the  pigeonholing  of  the  Freudians  with  the  mystics;  and  the  re- 
flex arc  concept  applied  to  perception  and  to  the  association  of 
ideas. 

Mysticism  is  illustrated  by  quotations  from  Plotinus  and  Dionys- 
ius,  as  well  as  from  Maeterlinck  and  other  modern  mystics.  It 
pretends  to  reach  a  "third  kind  of  knowledge,"  additional  to  that 
gained  through  the  senses  and  through  inference. 

This  third  and  highest  type  of  knowledge  is  to  be  had  only  in 
rare  moments  of  absorption  in  an  adored  object,  and  is  ineffable 
and  incommunicable.  The  author  concludes  that  this  "knowledge" 
amounts  to  emotion,  pure  and  simple,  with  the  sex  element  strong 
in  the  emotional  complex.  But  such  emotional  experience  has  no 
claims  to  scientific  recognition  as  a  source  of  knowledge. 

"Pseudo-mysticism,"  exemplified  by  belief  in  spirit  communi- 
cation and  telepathy,  differs  from  the  genuine  article  in  pretend- 
ing to  employ  logical  inference  in  reaching  its  conclusions,  but  its 
logic  is  constantly  vitiated  by  the  use  of  ambiguous  middle  terms, 


102  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOI'H  Y 

or  "sliding  terms,"  to  use  the  author's  expressive  words.  All 
mysticism  is  impatient  of  clearly  defined  terms,  and  of  the  whole 
painstaking  procedure  of  science,  and  tries  to  solve  the  mysteries 
of  life  by  uncritical  short  cuts. 

Scientific  procedure  is  strenuous  and  exacting.  It  requires 
constant  touch  with  facts,  parsimony  in  hypotheses,  experimental 
testing  of  hypotheses,  verification  of  results  by  independent  ob- 
servers, and  careful  definition  of  terms. 

Freud  is  shelved  with  the  mystics  by  the  canny  bookseller; 
Freud's  popular  appeal  is  to  the  love  for  the  mystical.  He  and 
his  followers  shrink  from  the  arduous  road  of  science,  and  pre- 
tend to  possess  knowledge  gained  in  some  other  way.  His  reason- 
ings are  vitiated  by  sliding  terms.  "Libido"  is  one  such  term; 
it  means  either  the  genuine  sex  motive,  or  something,  oh!  very 
much  broader,  just  according  to  the  momentary  needs  of  the  argu- 
ment. 

But  the  champion  sliding  term  is  the  Unconscious.  Sometimes 
the  unconscious  is  simply  a  working  hypothesis  which  proves  to 
work  well ;  and  sometimes  it  is  a  fact  from  which  there  is  no  escape. 
Sometimes  it  is  merely  a  "negative  concept  which  can  neither  be 
described  nor  defined";  and  sometimes  "we  are  already  familiar 
with  a  whole  series  of  positive  distinguishing  features  which  dif- 
ferentiate the  unconscious  psychic  material  from  the  rest,  the 
conscious  and  foreconscious. "  The  unconscious  is  not  merely  phys- 
iological— far  from  that!  It  is  a  kind  of  unconscious  conscious- 
ness, possessing  the  characteristics  of  consciousness  when  you  need 
them  for  the  purposes  of  your  argument,  but  not  when  they  would 
disturb  the  argument. 

The  Freudian  confusion  regarding  the  unconscious  is  in  part 
chargeable  against  the  long-standing  ambiguity  of  the  term,  "con- 
sciousness," which  has  meant  sometimes  "awareness,"  and  some- 
times "objects  of  which  one  is  directly  aware." 

From  this  grand  ambiguity  trouble  has  arisen  continually.  The  strife  between 
' '  interactionism  ' '  and  ' '  parallelism  ' ' :  the  conception  of  thought  and  conscious- 
ness as  stuff  and  things,  and  conversely,  the  conception  of  perceived  objects  as 
figments  of  ' '  mind  ' ' :  are  only  details  of  the  results,  of  this  confusion.  .  .  .  We 
eliminate  at  the  start  the  metaphysical  theories  of  epistemological  dualism  which 
have  played  so  pernicious  a  role  in  the  history  of  the  Anglo-German  psychology. 
Experience  does  not  give  us  directly  two  worlds  of  objects  physical  and  mental 
.  .  .  but  merely  a  world  of  objects  of  which  we  are  aware  (pp.  117,  120, 121). 

Though  the  author  does  not  speak  of  this  conclusion  of  his  as 
having  any  history,  it  seems  rather  reminiscent  of  things  that  have 
been  said  by  Wundt,  James,  and  other  representatives  of  the  ob- 
jectionable "Anglo-German  psychology." 

The  ambiguity  of  the  term  "  consciousness  "  is  undoubtedly  a  factor  con- 


BOOK  REVIEWS  103 

tributing  to  the  Freudian  confusion  over  the  "  unconscious."  .  .  .  But  this  ver- 
bal confusion  although  a  great  help  to  the  theory  of  ' '  unconscious  mind  ' '  is  not 
its  vital  source.  .  .  .  The  believer  in  ' '  unconscious  mental  processes  "...  might 
state  his  claim  as  follows :  In  addition  to  mental  processes,  i.e.,  organic  processes 
involving  consciousness  (awareness),  there  are  other  processes,  which  while  they 
do  not  involve  awareness,  involve  something  which  is  more  than  mere  physiological 
process:  something  resembling  consciousness,  but  not  conscious.  This  "  uncon- 
scious mental  ' '  factor  is  therefore  an  x,  an  unknown,  and  can  not  be  pointed  out 
in  any  definite  experience.  Such  an  hypothesis  might  be  made.  One  might  also 
hypothesize  a  y  factor,  a  z  factor,  and  an  infinity  of  other  factors,  all  equally 
unknown,  equally  beyond  experience  "  (pp.  125,  126). 

Since,  then,  the  hypothesis  of  an  unconscious  which  is  not  purely 
physiological  is  " removed  from  any  possibility  of  verification," 
it  is  entirely  valueless  to  science.  "What  its  value  or  appeal  may 
be  to  those  who  eagerly  embrace  it  the  author  does  not  stop  to 
inquire,  but  the  answer  is  suggested  in  a  highly  critical  review  of 
this  same  book  by  the  psychiatrist,  John  T.  MacCurdy,  M.D.1  Dr. 
MaeCurdy  bases  an  argument  for  the  unconscious,  as  against  "phys- 
iology," on  a  law  of  creative  synthesis,  which  can  be  seen  in  opera- 
tion throughout  the  realm  of  natural  science.  Any  synthetic  com- 
bination shows  properties  that  could  not  be  predicted  from  the 
known  properties  of  the  synthesized  elements — as,  for  example,  the 
crystalline  properties  of  common  salt  could  not  be  inferred  from 
the  known  properties  of  sodium  and  chlorine.  Analytical  chemis- 
try tells  you  of  the  elements  composing  the  compound,  but,  to  know 
the  compound  itself,  you  must  study  it  for  itself,  and  not  in  terms 
of  its  elements.  In  the  same  way,  biological  processes  may  be 
analyzed  into  physical  and  chemical  processes,  but  if  for  that  rea- 
son we  neglected  to  study  life  processes  as  such,  we  should  never 
know  much  biology.  In  just  the  same  way,  mental  processes  are 
composed  of  physiological  processes ;  but  if  we  are  satisfied  to  study 
them  only  from  the  physiological  side,  we  shall  never  know  much 
psychology.  Psychology,  the  contention  is,  must  stick  to  its  own 
order  of  facts,  and  to  its  own  concepts,  and  not  take  refuge  in 
physiological  interpretations.  Therefore,  it  has  need  for  the  con- 
cept of  unconscious  mental  processes.  The  value  of  the  "uncon- 
scious," accordingly,  is  simply  that  it  enables  one  to  keep  on  using 
psychological  terms,  even  when  dealing  with  unconscious  proces- 
ses. 

I  shall  not  undertake  any  criticism  of  this  interesting  conten- 
tion, except  to  remark  that  it  serves  better  as  a  justification  for 
the  "co-conscious,"  in  Morton  Prince's  sense,  than  for  Freud's 
particular  brand  of  unconscious.  In  double  personality  there  is 
some  evidence  of  a  secondary  synthesis  of  processes  lying  outside 

i  In  an  article  entitled,  ' '  Psychiatry  and  Scientific  Psychology, ' '  in  Mental 
Hygiene  for  April,  1921,  Vol.  5,  pp.  239-265. 


104  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPII  Y 

the  main  consciousness,  and  thus  some  reason  for  speaking  of  co- 
conscious  mental  processes;  but  in  the  case  of  dreams,  lapses,  queer 
impulses  and  fears,  and  iinanalyzed  motives,  I  do  not  know  that 
anyone  has  seriously  attempted  to  demonstrate  the  existence  of 
any  synthesis  additional  to  that  which  occurs  in  the  conscious 
process  itself.  The  conscious  process  may  show  disturbance  from 
some  source  outside  itself;  but.  unless  it  could  be  shown  that  this 
outside  source  consisted  of  processes  integrated  into  a  total  process 
of  the  mental  order,  we  should,  even  according  to  Dr.  MacCurdy's 
principle,  regard  it  as  physiological. 

As  against  the  unconscious  in  the  sense  of  a  storehouse  of  mem- 
ories, Professor  Dunlap  puts  the  case  with  striking  clearness: 

An  idea  is  not  a  thing  like  a  written  document  which,  after  being  in  the  active 
files  is  taken  out  and  stored  in  the  transfer  case.  It  is  more  like  an  act  such  as 
snapping  the  fingers  or  striking  a  blow.  I  may  snap  my  fingers  ten  times  in  suc- 
cession: but  no  one  supposes  that  the  snaps  have  an  individual  existence  after- 
wards and  are  somewhere  stored  away  as  snaps  which  are  no  longer  snapping.  No 
more  does  scientific  psychology  conceive  of  "  ideas  "  as  something  which  can  be 
stored  away  after  they  are  through  ' '  ideating. "  In  the  one  case  as  in  the  other, 
there  is  a  physiological  basis  which  is  modified  by  the  act  in  such  a  way  that  the 
act  can  be  repeated  at  a  future  time  (pp.  105-106). 

Professor  Dunlap,  as  the  reviewer  happens  to  know,  has  had 
his  eye  on  the  psychoanalysts  for  many  years,  and  his  remarks 
regarding  them  are  by  no  means  purely  "academic."  Some  of 
these  remarks  deserve  quotation. 

Reactions  which  later  become  a  part  of  the  general  sex  activity  are  found  in 
the  child,  and  therefore  pointed  out  as  evidence  of  sex  activity.  It  is  as  if  one 
should  claim  that  the  labored  breathing  produced  by  running  to  catch  a  street  car 
is  sexual  because  the  same  labored  breathing  may  occur  during  certain  stages  of 
sex  activity  (p.  60). 

As  is  readily  seen,  anything  that  can  be  dreamed  of  has  a  ready  sex  interpre- 
tation. So  that  the  telling  of  one 's  dreams  to  anyone  versed  in  the  gentle  art  of 
psychoanalysis  is  a  matter  in  which  your  feelings  of  delicacy  or  prudence  will  dic- 
tate if  you  realize  the  possibilities  (p.  71). 

This  .  .  .  characteristic  is  true  in  my  opinion  of  all  the  cases  in  which  the 
Freudian  analysis  ' '  strikes  oil. ' '  The  situation  which  is  discovered  through 
analysis  is  one  which  is  perfectly  well  known  to  the  patient,  but  the  patient  is 
loath  to  confess  it  and  does  not  realize  its  importance  (pp.  79-80). 

The  psychoanalyst  like  the  philosophical  mystic  is  essentially  tender-minded, 
and  can  not  endure  the  difficulties  and  disappointments  of  prosaic  science.  We 
are  not  surprised,  therefore,  to  find  over  and  above  the  essential  logical  fallacy  on 
which  the  system  is  based,  a  characteristic  nalvetl  in  reasoning  and  a  character- 
istic lack  of  orientation  in  facts  (p.  93). 

It  is  probable  that  psychoanalysts  do  produce  cures,  or  at  least  marked  alle- 
viation of  the  condition,  of  certain  cases.  In  other  cases  the  results  are  less  desir- 
able. The  question  of  vital  importance  is  whether  the  harm  done  by  the  general 
application  of  the  method  outweighs  the  good  accomplished  (p.  102). 

Sometimes,  a  complex  is  built  up  by  prolonged  psychoanalysis.    The  patient, 


BOOK  REVIEWS  105 

for  example,  is  convinced  that  his  neurosis  is  a  result  of  the  mother-complex;  at 
first  he  is  astonished  at  the  psychoanalyst's  discovery  but  by  the  copious  use  of 
symbolism,  by  the  perversion  of  all  the  patient  says  and  does,  with  that  end  in 
view,  he  is  finally  persuaded  that  the  complex  originated  in.  him,  and  not  in  the 
psychoanalyst.  By  constant  contemplation  of  the  complex  and  its  magic  relation- 
ships, all  the  symptoms  of  the  patient 's  troubles  become  closely  associated  with  it. 
If  now  the  psychoanalyst  can  exorcise  the  demon  he  has  raised  the  patient  may  be 
cured.  ...  In  many  cases,  however,  the  demon  refuses  to  be  exorcised  or  if  he 
complacently  leaves,  returns  shortly  with  ' '  seven  worse  than  himself, ' '  and  the 
latter  state  of  the  patient  is  worse  than  the  first  (pp.  102-103). 

Psychology  has  been  culpably  negligent  in  regard  to  the  study  of  the  desires, 
and  the  one  positive  service  which  the  Freudians  have  done  is  in  emphasizing  the 
incompetence  of  our  information  (and  also  of  their  own  information)  on  this 
important  subject  (p.  159). 

The  psychologist  who  needs  a  little  excitement  should  not  fail 
to  read  Dunlap's  book,  and  follow  it  with  some  of  the  reviews  of 
it  by  psychoanalysts.  Even  MacCurdy,  whose  long  review  con- 
tains much  serious  criticism,  starts  off  by  attempting  to  obscure 
the  issue  with  a  dust-cloud  of  professional  jealousies.  He  speaks 
of  an  "antagonism  at  present  existing  between  psychiatrists  and 
what  we  may  term  'academic  psychologists'  .  .  .  ."  "Both  the 
psychiatrists  and  the  psychologists  insist  that  they  are  the  ones  who 
should  direct  the  study  and  treatment  of  those  mental  abnormali- 
ties which  lead  to  social  unrest,  economic  insufficiency,  and  crime, 
as  well  as  to  frank  nervous  and  mental  disease. ' '  And  this  in  face 
of  Dunlap's  statement:  "The  development  of  a  sound  psycho- 
therapeutics  will  certainly  not  be  the  work  of  the  general  psy- 
chologist. But  when  it  is  developed,  it  will  be  developed  by 
psychopathologists  of  thorough  training  in  general  psychology" 
(p.  165).  Later  on  in  his  review,  referring  to  Dunlap's  strictures 
on  the  practise  of  psychoanalysis,  MacCurdy  exclaims:  "How  can  a 
college  professor,  presumably  attending  to  his  teaching  and  labora- 
tory work,  who  has  never  had  a  medical  education  and  has  never 
seen  a  patient  except  with  a  layman's  eyes — how  can  he  have  col- 
lected material  justifying  such  sweeping  conclusions?" 

Observe,  however,  the  reaction  of  an  anonymous  psychoanalyst 
in  the  Journal  of  Nervous  and  Mental  Diseases: 

The  work  in  question  is  just  such  as  one  would  expect  of  a  blind  rat  caught 
in  a  maze — defeat,  failure,  going  here  and  going  there,  misunderstanding,  mis- 
quoting, misreading,  a  tissue  of  stupid  distortions,  clumsy  misrepresentations,  and 
silly  evasions  based  upon  a  host  of  phobic  prejudices.  .  .  .  The  book,  to  us,  is  a 
ludicrous  defense  reaction.  Psychoanalysis  he  particularly  singles  out  as  a  special 
obstacle  to  science.  Piffle!  Nothing  can  obstruct  science  when  it  seeks  to  learn 
about  reality,  not  even  Dunlap  's  hobgoblin  antics.  The  psychoanalytic  hypotheses 
are  rather  object  lessons  to  make-believe  scientists  who  entrenched  behind  their 
academic  chairs  are  screeching  aloud  their  condemnation  of  many  things  they  not 
only  do  not  understand,  but  of  the  very  essence  of  which  they  seem  fundamentally 


106  JOURNAL  OF  PUILOSOVIl  Y 

incapable  ever  of  understanding  by  reason  of  their  emotional  limitations.  .  .  . 
One  would  like  further  to  characterize  this  unutterably  stupid  production,  but 
already  too  much  space  has  been  wasted  in  noticing  it  at  all. 

Certainly  Dunlap  has  produced  a  very  stimulating  essay! 

1 1  is  second  main  discussion,  on  the  "Reaction  Arc  Hypothesis," 
is  more  apt  to  arouse  the  psychologist.  The  reaction  arc  concept 
is  lh«>  <>ld  reflex  arc  concept,  "transformed  by  scientific  psychol- 
ogy" some  time  within  the  decade.  1910-1920.  Apparently  the 
transformation  in  question  has  been  the  author's  own  achievement, 
and  has  consisted  in  bringing  perception  and  the  association  of 
ideas  into  line  under  the  general  conception  of  complete  sensori- 
motor  reactions. 

The  reaction  arc  hypothesis  is  opposed  to  the  old  ' '  phrenologi- 
cal" conception  of  consciousness  as  "dependent  on  the  specialized 
functions  of  certain  groups  of  neurons  set  apart  from  the  other 
sorts  of  neurons"  (p.  132).  The  function  of  any  one  neuron  is  the 
same  as  that  of  any  other  neuron,  viz.,  "to  be  irritated  or  stimu- 
lated, and  to  irritate  in  turn  another  cell"  (p.  130).  "Mechani- 
cally, the  function  of  the  nervous  system  is  the  production  of 
responses:  that  is,  the  action  of  effectors  in  certain  ways,  conse- 
quent upon  specific  action  of  receptors.  .  .  .  Certain  definite 
responses,  or  reactions  of  the  organism,  are  accompanied  by,  or 
involve,  consciousness.  .  .  .  From  these  facts,  the  construction  of 
the  reaction-arc  hypothesis  is  inevitable.  Consciousness  (aware- 
ness) is  the  result  of,  or  the  accompaniment  of,  or  a  part  of  (the 
phrasing  is  for  the  present  immaterial)2  certain  reactions  involving 
the  activity  of  a  complete  arc  from  receptors  to  effectors"  (pp. 
133-134). 

Seeing  an  object,  for  example,  is  a  sensorimotor  reaction,  and 
requires  the  activity  of  a  "complete  arc." 

In  the  case  of  vision,  experiments  on  animals,  and  human  clinical  cases, 
make  this  point  clear.  Destroying  the  retinas;  cutting  the  optic  nerves;  cutting 
the  optic  tract  behind  the  brain-stem;  destroying  the  occipital  lobes  (of  the  cere- 
bral hemispheres)  to  which  the  optic  tracts  lead;  or  cutting  the  connections 
between  the  occipital  lobes  and  the  rest  of  the  cerebral  hemispheres:  produce 
the  one  and  the  same  results — blindness — by  interrupting  the  arcs  from  the  visual 
receptors  to  the  effector  systems,  and  destroying  the  possibility  of  a  visual  reac- 
tion. There  is  no  single  system  of  efferent  channels  from  the  hemispheres  which 
the  visual  reaction  need  follow:  hence,  to  block  completely  the  visual  reactions 
by  operation  on  the  efferent  side  of  the  arc,  all  the  efferent  channels  from  the 
hemispheres  would  have  to  be  cut.  This  would  cut  off  the  possibility  of  not  only 
visual,  but  all  reactions — and  the  patient  would  not  survive  (p.  135). 

This  last  is  certainly  unfortunate,  as  it  means  that  the  "reac- 
tion arc  hypothesis"  can  never  be  verified.     We  must,  it  would 
2  The  reviewer  would  prefer  to  say,  "  an  attribute  of." 


BOOK  REVIEWS  107 

seem,  relegate  this  hypothesis  to  the  limbo  of  hypotheses  "which 
are  by  their  nature  removed  from  any  possibility  of  verification," 
and  which  are  consequently  valueless.  "We  shall  never  know 
whether  a  person  could  see,  with  all  the  motor  channels  from  his 
brain  blocked  off ;  and,  since  we  can  not  know,  why  should  we  care  ? 

Still,  though  the  reaction  arc  hypothesis  can  never  be  positively 
verified,  it  might  perhaps  be  disproved  by  some  less  drastic  experi- 
ment. Some  deduction  from  the  hypothesis  might  conflict  with 
facts.  The  author  helps  us  on  our  way,  for  he  deduces  various 
consequences  of  his  general  hypothesis,  and  insists,  moreover,  that 
in  thus  applying  it  to  various  problems  he  does  not  need  to  intro- 
duce any  accessory  hypotheses. 

He  applies  the  hypothesis  to  the  case  of  the  conditioned  reflex. 
Here  we  have  two  stimuli,  originally  giving  two  different  reactions, 
but,  through  simultaneous  activity,  the  two  arcs  "become  con- 
nected in  the  cerebrum  so  that  the  current  flowing  in  over  the  af- 
ferent part  of  the  one,  may  now  flow  out  over  the  efferent  part  of 
the  other"  (p.  143).  Such  interconnection  of  reaction  arcs  in 
the  cerebrum  explains  "all  habit  formation,  including  both  the 
development  of  perception,  and  the  association  of  ideas"  (pp.  143- 
144). 

In  the  development  of  perception,  the  child  may  see  and  smell 
an  orange  simultaneously,  and  the  arcs  for  the  visual  reaction  and 
for  the  olfactory  reaction,  becoming  connected  in  the  cerebrum, 
enable  the  child  later  to  make  the  olfactory  response  to  the  visual 
stimulus. 

When  he  comes  to  the  association  of  "ideas,"  the  author  makes 
use  of  the  well-known  scheme  for  the  chaining  together  of  a  series 
of  movements  into  a  skilled  performance,  such  as  dancing.  The 
reaction  A,  terminating  in  the  contraction  of  certain  muscles,  ex- 
cites the  muscle  spindles  in  those  muscles,  and  thus  initiates  a 
second,  proprioceptive  reaction.  Along  with  this  proprioceptive 
reaction,  there  is  simultaneously  excited  by  an  external  stimulus 
the  movement  B ;  and  the  afferent  part  of  the  proprioceptive  arc  be- 
comes connected  in  the  cerebrum  with  the  efferent  part  of  the 
reaction  B,  quite  after  the  pattern  of  the  conditioned  reflex.  In 
this  way,  through  the  mediation  of  the  proprioceptive  arc,  move- 
ment B  becomes  attached  to  movement  A,  and  no  longer  requires 
its  own  original  stimulus. 

Now,  since  an  "idea"  is  to  be  conceived  as  a  sensorimotor  reac- 
tion, it  must  give  rise  to  a  proprioceptive  reaction  in  the  way  just 
explained,  and  this  proprioceptive  reaction  (or  the  afferent  half  of 
it,  extending  from  the  muscle  spindles  to  the  brain),  must  be  the 
intermediary  between  one  idea  and  the  next  in  an  associated  chain. 


108  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOl'll  Y 

If  ideas  are  dependent  on  reactions,  and  if  ideas  are  capable  of  association, 
it  must  be  that  the  ideational  reaction-arcs  are  of  such  a  nature  that  the  com- 
pletion of  one  reaction  may  initiate  another.  Since  reaction  arcs  terminate  in 
muscles  and  in  glands,  it  must  be  that  in  one  of  these  tissues  lie  the  necessary 
receptors  of  the  thought-arcs.  The  receptors  in  glands  are  as  yet  conjectural, 
and  the  glandular  response  is  not  of  such  a  nature  that  we  could  assume  it  to 
IK-  the  stimulus  of  reactions  as  prompt,  as  manifold,  and  as  finely  graded  as 
thought- reactions  apparently  are.  The  striped  muscles,  however,  are  provided 
with  a  plentitude  of  receptors  in  the  "  muscle  spindles,"  and  the  muscular 
responses  are  quick,  finely  graded,  and  of  great  complexity,  competent  to  initiate 
reactions  of  an  endless  variety.  The  muncle-receptors  are,  therefore,  in  all  prob- 
ability, the  beginnings  of  the  thought-arcs  (p.  147). 

Here  we  have  a  very  specific  deduction  from  the  general  reac- 
tion arc  hypothesis,  and  it  appears  that  this  deduction  can  be  put 
to  the  test  of  facts.  Since  the  muscle-spindle  intermediary  be- 
tween two  ideas  is  necessarily  "finely  graded,  and  of  great  com- 
plexity," and  also  highly  specific,  in  order  to  give  the  specific 
sequence  of  "ideas,"  it  certainly  should  follow  that  the  amputa- 
tion of  an  arm  or  a  leg  would  break  up  many  definite  associations. 
Loss  of  the  muscle  sense,  as  in  tabes,  should  break  up  associations 
of  ideas,  as  it  is  known  to  interfere  with  skilled  sequences  of  move- 
ment. Dr.  MacCurdy,  in  the  review  already  mentioned,  brings 
forward  still  more  striking  evidence: 

If  thought  originates  in  muscle  perceptions — and  he  evidently  means  this 
laterally — then  destruction  of  the  muscles  must  abolish  ideas.  There  are  many 
nervous  and  muscular  diseases  in  which  muscle  tissue  disappears  almost  entirely. 
In  these  thinking  is  usually  undisturbed.  It  is  possible  for  an  individual  to  live 
with  his  spinal  cord  divided  in  the  neck  so  that  there  is  no  connection  between 
the  brain  and  any  voluntary  muscle  except  those  of  the  head  and  neck  and  the 
diaphragm.  Thinking  is  still  possible  and  may  be  acute.  In  case  it  were  urged 
that  thoughts  were  initiated  by  the  vocal,  mouth  and  neck  muscles,  it  is  easy  to 
point  to  diseases  where  these  are  atrophied  or  have  their  nerve  supply  cut  off  from 
the  brain  (p.  255). 

This  appears  like  a  complete  disproof  of  the  reaction  arc  hypo- 
thesis as  applied  to  the  association  of  ideas.  The  only  line  of  de- 
fense which  our  author  has  prepared  against  such  an  attack  is 
briefly  indicated  in  the  following  passage: 

The  reactions  are  ultimately  abbreviated  or  short-circuited.  .  .  .  The  com- 
plete muscular  reaction  is  necessary  during  the  learning  process,  but  is  largely 
eliminated,  in  the  interests  of  economy,  after  the  series  have  been  thoroughly 
mechanized  (p.  153). 

But  against  the  adequacy  of  this  defense  it  may  be  urged:  (1) 
that,  according  to  the  hypothesis,  at  least  some  imperfectly  mechan- 
ized associations  must  be  lost  by  the  amputation  of  a  limb;  (2) 
that  amputation,  etc.,  should  be  a  very  serious  handicap  in  the 
formation  of  new  associations;  and  (3)  that  in  admitting  that, 


BOOK  REVIEWS  109 

after  mechanization,  a  thought  can  function  otherwise  than  as  a 
complete  arc,  the  author  has  notably  receded  from  the  boldness  of 
his  first  position.  At  first  he  held  that  "ideas  are  dependent  on 
reactions,"  i.e.,  on  complete  sensorimotor  reactions — since,  accord- 
ing to  the  reaction  arc  hypothesis,  all  mental  processes  are  so 
dependent.  But  now  we  learn  that  the  complete  reaction  is  largely 
eliminated,  and  still  the  ideational  processes  occur.  Apparently, 
some  deductions  from  his  general  hypothesis  have  seemed  unaccept- 
able to  the  author,  and  he  has  therefore  introduced  a  qualification 
which  amounts  to  abandoning  the  hypothesis  in  its  original  clean- 
cut  form. 

As  a  matter  of  fact,  he  did  not  succeed  in  holding  fast  to  the 
hypothesis  even  while  applying  it  to  the  conditioned  reflex  and  to 
perception.  He  dealt  not  in  complete  arcs  as  his  units,  but  in 
half-arcs.  The  afferent  half  of  one  arc  became  connected  in  the 
cerebrum  with  the  efferent  half  of  another  arc.  In  the  same  way, 
though  he  began  his  interpretation  of  the  association  of  ideas  with 
the  presupposition  that  he  must  deal  in  complete  arcs,  he  had  im- 
mediately to  split  up  his  proprioceptive  arc,  and  let  the  afferent 
half  of  it  function  alone  in  mediating  between  one  idea  and  an- 
other. Any  theory  which  dealt  consistently  with  complete  arcs 
would  have  to  seek  the  formation  of  new  linkages  in  the  periphery! 

It  is  impossible  to  write  a  physiological  psychology  in  terms  of 
the  "complete  arc"  as  unit.  Learning,  whether  motor,  perceptive, 
or  "ideational,"  requires  a  smaller  unit.  Facilitation  and  inhibi- 
tion require  a  smaller  unit.  In  the  simplest  cases  of  learning,  such 
as  the  conditioned  reflex,  the  half  arc  seems  to  make  a  workable 
unit.  In  reactions  that  involve  a  series  of  cerebral  steps  between 
the  sensory  stimulus  and  the  motor  response  (as  in  the  case  of  see- 
ing a  signal,  knowing  what  it  signifies,  and  responding  with  an 
appropriate  skilled  movement),  the  unit  is  smaller  than  a  half  arc, 
and  amounts  to  a  single  one  of  the  cerebral  steps.  In  our  author's 
fundamental  statement,  "that  the  function  of  any  one  neuron  is 
the  same  as  that  of  any  other  neuron,  viz.,  to  be  irritated  or  stimu- 
lated, and  to  irritate  in  turn  another  cell,"  there  is  certainly 
nothing  that  demands  the  "complete  arc"  as  the  unit.  Rather, 
the  unit  should  be  the  stimulation  of  one  neuron  by  another.  This 
is  the  single  step  in  any  psychoneural  process;  and  there  is  no 
reason  compelling  us  to  adopt  any  larger  unit  as  the  ultimate  unit 
of  physiological  psychology. 

R.  S.  WOOD  WORTH. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


110  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOVU  Y 

JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  BRITISH  JOURNAL  OF  PSYCHOLOGY.  June  1921. 
The  Instinctive  Behavior  and  Enjoyment:  C.  LLOYD  MORGAN  (pp. 
l-30).-"If  I  were  asknl:  'What  are  you  driving  at  in  this  and  so 
much  else  that  you  have  written  on  instinct!  '  the  reply  would  be: 
'My  aim  has  been  to  find  its  place,  as  defined,  in  the  evolutionary 
story  of  life  and  of  consciousness.'  '  The  manner  in  which  the 
mind  acts  as  a  directive  agency  in  determining  the  course  of  in- 
stinctive behavior  and  the  way  in  which  the  mind  acts  as  an  impulsive 
agency,  as  the  driving  power  behind  the  observed  behavior  must 
both  be  included;  otherwise  one  has  only  a  description  in  terms  of 
observed  facts  which  are  merely  generalizations  that  formulate  the 
plan  of  the  facts.  7s  a  Fatigue  Test  Possible f  B.  Muscio  (pp. 
31— 46). -An  essential  pre-condition  of  experimentation  designed  to 
obtain  a  fatigue  test  is  the  knowledge  that  different  degrees  of  fatigue 
are  present  at  certain  times.  It  is  justifiable  to  experiment  with  the  ob- 
ject of  finding  a  rapid  and  convenient  fatigue  test.  It  is  recommended 
that  the  term  fatigue  be  absolutely  banished  from  precise  scientific 
discussion,  and  that  the  problem  to  be  investigated  be  defined  as  the 
determination  of  the  effects  of  different  kinds  and  amounts  of  work 
(activity)  upon  mental  and  physiological  functions:  that  is,  that  the 
kind  and  amount  of  work  be  correlated  directly  with  changes  in 
psycho-physiological  functions,  and  not  (as  at  present)  indirectly  by 
means  of  fatigue.  A  Preliminary  Study  of  the  Reproduction  of 
Hand  Movements:  C.  RODRIGO  LAVIN  (pp.  47-52). -The  problem  was 
to  determine  the  most  favorable  conditions  for  the  learning  and  re- 
production of  hand  movements.  The  conclusions  indicate  that  (1) 
in  the  early  stages  of  practise  all  of  the  subjects  attended  to  the 
form  of  a  movement  rather  than  to  its  extent;  (2)  the  points  of  move- 
ment most  speedily  and  accurately  learned  were  the  beginning  and 
end,  and  wherever  sharp  changes  of  direction  occurred;  (3)  different 
forms  of  hand  movement  were  very  readily  coalesced  or ' '  condensed. ' ' 
Suggestibility  with  and  without  Prestige  in  Children:  F.  AVELING 
and  H.  L.  HARGREAVES  (pp.  53-75). -The  results  show  that  general 
suggestibility  is  greatly  modified  by  the  specific  conditions  and  ele- 
ments of  the  whole  situation,  which  vary  in  individual  cases,  accord- 
ing to  experience  of  it  and  knowledge  of  it.  There  is  no  ascertained 
tendency  for  suggestibility  to  go  with  other  "general"  factors  such 
as  general  intelligence,  perseveration,  oscillation,  or  motor  dexterity. 
There  is  small  correlation  between  it  and  common  sense  regarded  as 
consisting  largely  of  affective  and  conative  elements;  but  none  if 
common  sense  is  considered  as  a  purely  copnative  quality.  Recent 
Work  in  Experimental  ^Esthetics:  EDWARD  BUIAOUGH  (pp.  76-99).- 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  111 

No  work  of  an  experimental  kind  has,  to  the  writer 's  knowledge,  been 
carried  out  since  1914,  and  what  is  meant  'by  "recent"  are  experi- 
ments undertaken  between  1900  and  1914.  It  is  the  lack  of  experi- 
mental work  during  the  last  six  years  which  prompted  the  writer 
to  survey  the  earlier  results.  The  writer  emphasizes  that  until  the 
conceptions  with  which  philosophies  of  art  are  wont  to  operate  are 
illuminated  by  actually  and  accurately  observed  experiences  of  many 
persons,  instead  of  being  vaguely  apprehended  and  rashly  general- 
ized personal  introspections  of  their  authors,  little  will  be  done  by 
interminable  discussions  of  such  topics.  Critical  Notice:  G.  UDNY 
YULE  (pp.  100-107).  A  review  of  the  revised  and  expanded  edition 
of  The  Essentials  of  Mental  Measurement  by  William  Brown  and 
Godfrey  H.  Thomson.  Publications  Recently  Received.  British  Psy- 
chological Society  Membership  List. 

Brierly,  Susan  S.  An  Introduction  to  Psychology.  London :  Meth- 
uen  &  Co.  1921.  Pp.  152.  5  s. 

Dopter,  M.  Les  Maladies  Infectieuses  pendant  la  Guerre  (fitude 
epidemiologique).  Paris:  Felix  Alcan.  1921.  Pp.  308.  9  fr. 

Mandonnet,  P.  and  Destrez,  J.  Bibliographic  Thomiste.  Le  Saul- 
choir,  Kain,  Belgium.  1921.  Pp.  xxi  +116.  10  fr. 

Moore,  Jared  Sparks.  The  Foundations  of  Psychology.  Princeton 
University  Press.  1921.  Pp.  239.  $3. 

Myers,  Caroline  E.  and  Garry  C.  Measuring  Minds:  An  Examiner's 
Manual  to  Accompany  the  Myers  Mental  Measure.  New  York 
and  Chicago :  Newson  &  Co.  1921.  Pp.  5.5. 

Sellars,  Hoy  Wood.  Evolutionary  Naturalism.  Chicago  and  Lon- 
don: The  Open  Court  Publishing  Co.  1922.  Pp.  xii+343. 
$2.50. 

Smallwood,  William  Martin.  Man — the  Animal.  New  York:  The 
Macmillan  Co.  1922.  Pp.  xiv+223.  $2.50. 

de  Unamuno,  Miguel.  The  Tragic  Sense  of  Life  in  Men  and  in 
Peoples.  Translated  by  J.  E.  Crawford  Flitch.  (With  an  In- 
troductory Essay  by  Salvador  de  Madariaga.)  London:  Mac- 
millan &  Co.  1921.  Pp.  xxxv  +332.  17  s. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

A  copy  of  the  second  edition  of  Moral  Values  and  the  Idea  of  God, 
by  W.  R.  Sorley  has  recently  reached  us.  These  Gifford  Lectures  of 
1914  and  1915  were  originally  published  in  1920,  and  were  reviewed 
in  our  issue  of  November  18,  1920.  The  author  prefixes  this  second 


112  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

edition  with  the  following  brief  preface:  "In  preparing  this  edition 
I  have  kept  in  view  the  criticisms  of  the  book  which  have  come  into 
my  hands,  but  I  have  not  introduced  new  matters  of  controversy. 
The  few  errors  which  have  been  pointed  out  by  others  or  discovered 
by  myself  have  been  corrected  silently ;  and  certain  portions  of  the 
argument,  where  experience  has  shown  that  there  was  a  possibility 
of  misunderstanding,  have  been  made  clearer  and  more  pointed  in 
statement.  The  only  addition  which  needs  to  be  recorded  is  a  short 
discussion  on  the  relation  of  foreknowledge  to  freedom,  a  topic  dealt 
with  too  dogmatically  in  the  first  edition." 

The  Southwestern  Philosophical  Association  held  its  second  an- 
nual meeting  on  December  28,  1921,  as  the  guest  of  Occidental  Col- 
lege. Dr.  Bernard  C.  Ewer,  of  Pomona  College,  presented  a  paper 
on  "A  Dilemma  in  Ethics,"  and  Dr.  James  Main  Dixon,  of  the 
University  of  Southern  California,  one  on  "The  Philosophy  of  Sym- 
pathy" as  an  expression  of  French  and  Scottish  thinking.  A  dis- 
cussion of  Rivers 's  treatment  of  instinct  and  of  the  unconscious  was 
offered  by  Dr.  John  Scott,  of  the  University  College  of  Cardiff, 
Wales,  and  this  year  Mills  professor  at  the  University  of  California. 
The  following  officers  were  elected  for  the  coming  year:  President. 
Ralph  Tyler  Flewelling,  University  of  Southern  California;  Secre- 
tary-Treasurer, Henry  Nelson  Wieman,  Occidental  College ;  Member 
of  the  Executive  Committee,  Bernard  Capen  Ewer,  Pomona  College. 
The  next  meeting  of  the  Association  will  be  at  Easter  time. 

The  Philosophy  Section  of  the  Oklahoma  Educational  Associa- 
tion met  on  Thursday,  February  9,  in  Oklahoma  City.  Dr.  Melvin 
Rigg  of  Oklahoma  City  College  presented  a  paper  on  the  History  of 
the  Logos  Doctrine,  which  discussed  St.  John 's  conception  of  Christ 
as  the  Word  of  God,  together  with  the  antecedents  of  the  Logos  doc- 
trine in  Greek  philosophy,  and  Hebrew  theology. 

The  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY  has  been  unable  for  some  time  to 
fill  orders  for  complete  files  because  of  the  lack  of  two  early  numbers, 
Vol.  II,  No.  5,  and  Vol.  Ill,  No.  1  (March  2,  1905  and  January  4. 
1906).  If  any  of  our  readers  have  copies  of  one  or  both  of  these 
issues  which  they  would  be  willing  to  part  with,  the  JOURNAL  would 
be  very  glad  to  buy  them  at  the  rate  of  50  cents  a  copy. 


VOL.    XIX,  No.  5.  MARCH  2,  li,22 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


A  SUGGESTION  REGARDING  ESTHETICS 

IN  the  past  esthetics  has  been  approached  from  three  different 
angles — the  critical,  the  philosophical,  and  the  psychological. 
On  the  whole  these  three  methods  of  approach  are  fairly  distinct, 
and  generally  a  book  on  esthetic  subjects  can  be  unhesitatingly 
placed  in  one  of  these  three  classes  to  the  exclusion  of  th<Tother 
two. 

Examples  of  the  critical  method  of  approach  are  in  literature 
such  books  as  those  by  Matthew  Arnold,  Moulton,  Brander 
Mathews ;  in  painting  those  by  Van  Dyke,  Berenson,  Harold  Speed ; 
in  music  those  by  Dickenson,  Prout,  and  the  like.  The  approach 
is  personal.  These  men  look  at  a  work  of  art  in  the  same  way 
that  a  newspaper  critic  does ;  indeed,  many  of  these  men  were  news- 
paper critics  at  one  time  in  their  lives,  and  have  come  to  differ 
from  the  general  run  of  critics  only  by  the  superiority  of  their 
judgment  and  power  of  expression.  They  are  looked  upon  as  ex- 
perts like  wine  tasters.  The  public  wants  their  opinion  on  art,  and 
they  give  it  to  the  best  of  their  ability.  From  the  point  of  view 
of  the  public  it  is  a  matter  of  faith  and  authority;  from  the  point 
of  view  of  the  critic  a  matter  of  long  experience  crystallized  into 
a  sort  of  intuition. 

It  is  entirely  a  personal  matter.  That  does  not  mean  that  it 
is  a  capricious  matter,  a  question  of  mere  opinion.  The  opinion 
of  a  trained  critic  is  never  a  mere  opinion.  It  is  the  outcome  of 
long  experience.  What  I  mean  by  saying  it  is  a  personal  matter 
is  that  it  is  wholly  a  relation  between  a  single  critic  and  an  inquir- 
ing public.  His  judgment  is  what  is  wanted,  and  the  basis  of  his 
judgment  is  a  secondary  matter.  His  intuitive  reaction  is  sought, 
not  the  rational  and  scientific  background  for  the  reaction.  Often 
when  a  critic  is  asked  why  he  holds  an  opinion,  he  finds  it  very 
hard  to  explain.  And  that  is  no  paradox,  for  a  golfer  can  hit  a 
ball  squarely  and  yet  find  it  impossible  to  explain  how  he  did  it. 
It  is  because  a  critic  often  does  not  know  the  reasons  for  his  judg- 
ment that  he  falls  to  ridiculing  a  work  of  art,  concealing  his  em- 
barrassment with  laughter.  The  smaller  the  critic  the  truer  this 
is,  for  a  great  critic  is  willing  to  stake  his  reputation  on  his  judg- 
ment whether  he  can  give  reasons  or  not. 

113 


114  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


if  a  critic  docs  give  reasons  they  are  likely  to  be  in  the 
nature  of  aphorisms,  half  truths  half  recognized  as  such,  just  one 
remove  from  an  immediate  intuitive  judgment.  And  in  general 
the  more  universal  and  sweeping  the  judgments  a  critic  makes, 
the  less  valuable;  just  the  opposite  from  science  where  the  more 
universal  the  law  the  more  valuable.  The  critical  method  of  ap- 
proach is  not  scientific,  not  disinterested,  and  dispassionate,  accept- 
in^  tin-  authority  and  experience  of  nobody  but  only  the  logic  of 
the  facts;  but  on  the  contrary  is  wholly  a  matter  of  personal  ex- 
perience and  authority.  It  is,  therefore,  not  a  suitable  method 
for  a  science  of  esthetics. 

Now,  by  saying  that  the  critical  method  is  not  scientific,  and 
therefore  that  it  is  not  applicable  to  esthetics,  I  am  by  no  means 
saying  that  it  is  a  useless  approach.  On  the  contrary,  if  we  should 
ever  have  an  established  science  of  esthetics  with  a  vast  classifica- 
tion of  facts  and  verified  laws,  we  should  still  want  critics  to  be 
doing  then  just  what  we  are  doing  now.  For  a  critic  is  to  esthet- 
ics a  good  deal  what  a  doctor  is  to  physiology.  There  is  nothing 
a  doctor  knows  that  is  not  to  be  found  in  physiology,  yet  doctors 
have  not  outlived  their  usefulness.  We  still  call  upon  them  to 
diagnose  our  ailments,  and  consider  them  much  better  for  that  pur- 
pose than  physiologists.  And  so  in  the  future,  if  the  future  haa 
in  store  for  us  a  science  of  esthetics,  we  shall  appeal  not  to  an 
esthetician  but  to  a  critic  for  a  judgment  about  any  new  school  of 
art.  And  presumably  the  critic  of  this  future  will  have  studied 
esthetics  as  the  modern  doctor  studies  physiology,  and  will  be  as 
much  superior  to  the  modern  critic  as  the  surgeon  of  the  present 
is  to  the  barber  of  the  middle  ages. 

The  second  method  of  approach  was  philosophical.  Examples 
of  this  method  are  the  esthetic  writings  of  Kant,  Hegel,  Croce, 
Bosanquet,  and  the  like.  The  assumption  behind  this  method  is 
that  esthetics  is  a  branch  of  philosophy  inseparable  from  it,  and 
therefore  to  be  treated  philosophically.  The  first  thing  to  do  is  by 
a  process  of  analysis  to  define  beauty,  and  then  we  may  draw  the 
consequences.  The  logic  of  this  approach  is  quite  convincing  ;  for, 
it  is  argued,  how  can  we  know  that  anything  is  beautiful  until  we 
first  know  what  beauty  is?  It  would  appear  that  our  first  effort 
should  be  to  define  beauty. 

But  in  spite  of  the  plausibility  of  this  argument  there  seems 
to  be  a  quantity  of  evidence  from  external  sources  to  show  that 
we  can  learn  a  great  deal  about  a  subject  without  waiting  for  a 
definition  of  it,  indeed  that  perhaps  the  definition  has  to  wait  until 
we  have  learned  this  great  deal  about  the  subject.  We  have  a 
very  respectable  science  of  biology  though  we  are  still  uncertain 


A  SUGGESTION  REGARDING  ESTHETICS  115 

about  the  definition  of  life,  and  a  very  respectable  science  of 
chemistry  though  we  are  still  uncertain  about  the  definition  of 
matter.  Furthermore,  we  now  feel  well  assured  that  our  defini- 
tions of  life  and  matter  never  could  have  amounted  to  much  prior 
to  our  sciences  of  biology  and  chemistry  which  we  developed  with- 
out finished  definitions.  Of  course,  we  had  crude  definitions  to 
keep  us  from  going  completely  astray,  definitions  that  we  were 
willing  to  change  from  time  to  time  as  the  facts  seemed  to  indi- 
cate, but  both  of  these  sciences  have  been  developed  without  that 
finished  definition  which  philosophically  seemed  to  be  the  first 
prerequisite  of  science.  Even  mathematics  does  not  follow  the 
philosophical  method.  The  definitions  of  number  and  quantity 
have  undergone  various  changes  as  one  discovery  or  another  would 
suggest,  and  only  recently  have  been  redefined.  Even  mathematics, 
the  so-called  deductive  science,  developed  without  a  perfect  defini- 
tion of  its  subject  matter.  That  finished  definition,  judging  from 
the  testimony  of  the  sciences,  is  the  last  thing  to  be  determined  in 
the  development  of  knowledge  rather  than  the  first. 

The  science  of  esthetics,  therefore,  does  not  have  to  wait  until 
philosophy  can  give  it  a  finished  definition  of  its  subject  before  it 
can  proceed  to  accumulate  data.  All  it  needs  is  some  working 
definition.  A  father  does  not  keep  his  son  at  home  until  he  can 
send  him  into  the  world  with  a  complete  fortune;  he  gives  his 
son  some  pocket  money  and  sends  him  into  the  world  to  make  his 
fortune.  And  now,  of  course,  I  do  not  mean  that  speculation  as  to 
what  that  ultimate  definition  will  be  is  valueless.  Our  curiosity 
is  impatient,  and  we  wish  to  speculate  about  the  complete  nature 
of  things  before  we  have  complete  knowledge.  To  see  things  as 
a  whole  as  well  as  possible  is  the  function  of  philosophy,  and  that 
is  no  little  thing.  But  philosophy  can  still  continue  to  seek  the 
true  definition  of  beauty  while  the  science  of  esthetics  is  plodding 
in  the  dust  of  facts,  and  may  perhaps  be  willing  occasionally  to 
pick  up  some  slight  suggestion  out  of  the  dust.  Philosophic  inter- 
est in  the  ultimate  nature  of  life  and  matter  does  not  seem  to  have 
been  damped  by  scientific  activity  in  biology  and  chemistry. 

The  third  method  of  approach  was  psychological.  Of  this  the 
work  of  Lipps,  Him,  Fechner,  and  a  swarm  of  men  whose  articles 
appear  in  psychological  periodicals,  are  typical.  The  implied  argu- 
ment of  all  these  men  is  that  since  the  appreciation  of  beauty 
is  a  conscious  experience,  esthetics  is  necessarily  a  branch  of  psy- 
chology and  obviously  falls  under  the  domain  of  the  emotions. 
When  the  psychology  of  the  emotions  is  developed,  it  will  then  be 
a  simple  matter  to  apply  the  general  principles  to  the  experience 
of  esthetic  appreciation.  Meanwhile,  we  can  carry  on  a  few  simple 
experiments  on  sensory  appreciation,  balance,  symmetry,  etc. 


116  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

1  would  be  far  from  denying  the  value  of  these  simple  experi- 
ments. They  have  given  a  great  deal  of  important  information, 
but  I  believe  any  candid  psychologist  would  be  ready  to  admit 
that  the  whole  sum  of  information  so  gained  or  that  ever  will  be 
so  gained  would  leave  one  only  on  the  doorstep  of  esthetics.  Sup- 
pose we  knew  all  that  psychological  experiment  could  tell  us  about 
balance,  symmetry,  and  linear  combination,  it  would  still  be  a 
long  distance  from  all  these  facts  to  the  Amiens  Cathedral.  The 
rest  of  it,  the  psychologist  would  say,  lay  in  the  psychology  of  the 
emotions  and  the  higher  processes.  Granted,  and  so  esthetics  must 
wait  until  the  psychology  of  the  emotions  is  complete.  Thus  psy- 
chology would  tie  esthetics  to  her  apron  strings  with  the  same  con- 
vincing logic  that  philosophy  would  tie  it  to  hers. 

But  how  escape  from  psychology,  it  may  be  asked.  Well,  how 
did  psychology  escape  from  philosophy?  There  is  no  greater  fal- 
lacy than  the  belief  that  the  foundations  of  a  science  must  be  firm 
before  work  can  begin  on  the  science  itself.  The  metaphor  is  mis- 
leading, for  every  material  advance  in  the  erection  of  the  super- 
structure brings  about  a  corresponding  advance  in  the  making  of 
the  foundations.  A  better  metaphor  would  be  of  a  tree,  which 
must  have  roots  to  stand,  but  whose  roots  grow  with  the  growth  of 
the  trunk  and  limbs.  With  such  a  metaphor  in  mind  it  would  be 
no  paradox  that  a  seedling  science  should  require  only  a  seedling's 
roots,  and  not  the  broad  and  systematic  radication  of  an  ancient 
and  matured  science.  Esthetics  is  a  seed  dropped  from  the  seed- 
pods  of  psychology,  and  may  sprout  at  once  in  independent  soil. 

Economics  is  also  a  seedling  from  psychology  of  such  rapid 
growth  that  it  is  almost  overshadowing  the  parent  tree.  For  eco- 
nomics takes  its  departure  too  from  conscious  experience.  It  is 
the  science  of  a  certain  limited  group  of  human  desires — viz.,  those 
that  lead  to  exchange.  And  the  first  rootlet  that  fed  the  science 
and  held  it  in  its  place  was  the  concept  of  the  economic  man, 
which  on  analysis  proves  to  be  an  assumption  of  the  nature  of 
human  desires.  On  that  assumption  the  science  grew  to  consider- 
able size.  The  assumption  has  since  proved  false,  but  it  served 
to  nourish  the  science  while  it  was  young. 

A  similar  assumption  is  what  esthetics  needs  in  order  to  develop 
into  a  science.  We  shall  never  get  such  a  science  if  we  wait  for  the 
intuitive  judgments  of  critics  to  become  organized  into  a  consis- 
tent system:  we  shall  never  get  it  if  we  wait  till  philosophy  gives 
us  a  perfect  definition  of  beauty :  we  shall  not  get  it  if  we  wait  for 
psychology  to  clear  up  the  field  of  consciousness.  The  three  tradi- 
tional ways  of  approach  to  esthetics  begin  splendidly  paved  but 
soon  dwindle  to  ribbon  roads  and  presently  are  lost  in  underbrush 


A  SUGGESTION  REGARDING  ESTHETICS  117 

and  tangle.  Esthetics  must  build  its  own  road  if  it  would  be 
developed.  And  all  that  it  needs  for  starting  that  road  is  a  work- 
ing unit. 

Now,  a  working  unit  is  a  form  of  working  hypothesis,  and  in 
this  case  at  least  it  should  not  be  made  too  exact  or  confining,  or 
it  will  destroy  its  own  usefulness.  If  the  staging  for  a  building 
is  made  so  solid  as  to  resemble  the  finished  structure,  it  will  cut 
out  the  light  and  hinder  if  not  make  impossible  the  erection  of  the 
building  for  which  it  was  to  be  a  means.  The  working  unit  for  an 
independent  esthetics  should  be  sufficiently  open,  and  free,  yes, 
and  ambiguous,  to  allow  as  large  a  number  of  men  to  cooperate 
under  it  as  possible,  and  as  large  a  number  of  pertinent  facts  to  be 
distributed  under  it  as  possible.  The  aim  of  a  working  unit  is  not 
to  bring  exact  results  but  to  bring  big  results. 

If  there  are  people  who  think  that  big  results  can  only  be 
obtained  through  exactness,  these  people  are  much  mistaken.  This 
is  a  fallacy  similar  to  the  one  mentioned  earlier,  the  belief  that  a 
dependent  science  can  only  be  developed  if  the  fundamental  science 
upon  which  it  depends  has  been  completed.  Science  does  not  build 
itself  up  from  preestablished  exact  units,  but  moves  progressively 
from  inexactness  to  greater,  and  greater,  and  greater  exactness. 
Physics  is  not  yet  the  exact  science  it  will  be.  Exactness  is  derived 
from  inexactness.  We  lose  all  if  we  try  to  make  our  working  unit 
of  esthetics  exact  at  once,  for  the  chances  are  we  shall  make  it 
exact  in  the  wrong  direction.  We  must  be  satisfied  to  begin  with 
an  inexact  unit. 

Furthermore,  in  the  early  stage  of  a  science  it  is  highly  ad- 
vantageous to  employ  a  unit  that  is  easily  understood,  a  more  or 
less  common-sense  concept.  For  in  the  early  stages  of  a  science 
there  is  no  established  school  to  train  men  to  a  method  and  a  vo- 
cabulary. The  men  working  in  the  science  will  be  widely  scattered 
and  largely  out  of  communication  with  one  another.  If  a  too  recon- 
dite term  is  used  by  one  man,  it  is  likely  to  be  passed  over  by  the 
others  who  will  substitute  some  favorite  term  of  their  own,  and 
presently  there  will  be  no  one  unit,  but  the  same  chaos  we  now 
have.  A  recondite  term  is  like  a  word  in  a  dialect :  a  common-sense 
term  has  a  universality  and  a  consolidating  power  which  is  worth 
more  than  all  else  in  a  science  struggling  for  life. 

A  common-sense  concept,  not  too  exact,  capable  of  embracing 
many  facts,  and  of  bringing  into  at  least  seeming  agreement  many 
men — these  are  the  requirements  of  a  working  unit  in  esthetics. 
Such  a  unit,  I  believe,  has  been  groping  its  way  towards  recogni- 
tion in  the  last  few  decades.  It  is  the  liking  of  a  thing  for  itself  in 
contrast  to  the  valuing  of  a  thing  as  a  means  to  something  else. 


118  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

It  has  been  variously  called  "intrinsic,"  "disinterested,"  "inde- 
pendent," "primary"  value.  It  simply  marks  off  the  attitude 
opposite  to  the  practical  attitude. 

Nearly  all  prominent  estheticians  of  the  last  century  have  this 
concept  at  the  core  of  their  definitions.  So  with  Bosanquet,  Croce, 
Santayana,  Fechner,  to  mention  only  a  few  of  the  greatest.  And 
notice  to  what  different  philosophical  schools  these  men  belong. 
These  men  differ  from  each  other  in  their  attempts  to  make  their 
definitions  exact.  They  have  in  common  the  core  of  that  inexact 
common-sense  concept  of  things  valued  for  themselves  independent 
of  all  practical  considerations.  They  feel,  however,  that  this  con- 
cept is  too  wide  and  attempt  to  narrow  it  and  make  it  exact.  But 
the  moment  they  attempt  to  narrow  it  they  are  led  one  this  way 
and  one  that  according  to  their  personal  predispositions  and  meta- 
physical leanings.  The  consequence  is  that  they  all  begin  t<> 
quarrel  among  themselves  about  the  trimmings  of  their  definitions 
instead  of  getting  down  to  work  and  accumulating  facts  under  the 
core  of  their  definitions.  If  these  men  would  let  the  trimmings  go, 
they  could  cooperate  and  work  in  harmony.  Not  that  they  should 
totally  forget  their  disagreements,  for  out  of  such  disagreements 
would  ultimately  come  the  possibility  of  bringing  greater  precision 
into  the  working  definition.  But  the  emphasis  should  be  thrown 
on  their  points  of  agreement  rather  than  on  those  of  disagreement 
if  progress  is  to  be  made  in  an  independent  science  of  esthetics. 
But,  of  course,  none  of  these  men  had  any  such  aim  in  mind.  All 
I  wish  to  point  out  is  that  the  unit  I  am  proposing  here  is  not 
one  I  have  arbitrarily  made  up,  but  one  that  already  exists  at  the 
bottom  of  most  modern  esthetic  theory.  And  all  that  is  needed  is 
to  bring  this  crude  core  out  into  the  light  in  all  its  starkness  and 
uncouthness,  and  in  spite  of  its  unprepossessing  appearance  to 
accept  it. 

What  we  want  at  present  is  not  a  finished  definition  of  beauty, 
but  something  to  gather  facts  about  from  which  generalizations 
may  be  made  and  perhaps  laws  determined,  laws  which  in  turn  will 
eventually  refine  and  make  precise  the  uncouth  unit  to  which  they 
owed  their  discovery.  The  unit  will  circumscribe  a  field  of  experi- 
ence which  contains  our  esthetic  facts,  and  that  is  all  we  have  a 
right  to  ask  for  in  the  beginning.  If  there  is  hope  for  a  concrete 
science  of  esthetics  in  the  near  future  it  lies  in  some  such  concept 
as  the  one  we  have  been  considering.  It  assuredly  does  not  lie  in 
criticism,  or  philosophy,  or  psychology. 

STEPHEN  C.  PEPPER. 

UNIVERSITY  or  CALIFORNIA. 


ESTHETIC  VALVES  119 

ESTHETIC  VALUES  AND  THEIR  INTERPRETATION 

THE  paper  of  Mr.  Pepper  on  a  point  in  esthetics *  raises  a  num- 
ber of  questions  that  would  be  interesting  to  discuss  at  length. 
The  following  remarks  are  not  offered  as  such  a  discussion  and  no 
more  is  claimed  for  them  than  that  they  happen  to  be  my  opinions 
at  present. 

Mr.  Pepper  puts  excellently  the  contrast  between  esthetic  criti- 
cism and  scientific  formulation.  Any  critical  estimate  involves  so 
much  of  the  critic's  personal  equation,  Mr.  Pepper  thinks,  that  it 
tends  to  be  the  reverse  of  scientific;  it  is  not  disinterested  nor  dis- 
passionate. We  should  be  suspicious  of  sweeping  judgments  in 
esthetic  criticism.  But  in  science  just  the  opposite  is  true,  "where 
the  more  universal  the  law,  the  more  valuable. ' '  The  critical  method 
of  approach  is,  therefore,  not  a  suitable  method  for  a  science  of 
esthetics. 

This  is  nearly  all  true,  but,  I  suspect,  not  for  the  reasons  Mr. 
Pepper  has  in  mind.  I  agree  that  the  method  of  "criticism"  is  not 
scientific ;  I  agree,  moreover,  that  it  can  not  possibly  be  made  so,  no 
matter  how  disinterested  and  dispassionate  the  critic  might  be.  But 
that  is  not  because  critical  judgments  are  affected  by  a  personal 
equation,  which,  perhaps,  they  usually  are.  It  is  because  the  judg- 
ment of  criticism  deals  with  an  individual  in  its  uniqueness,  while  a 
judgment  of  the  scientific  type  deals  with  a  universal,  i.e.,  with 
something  intended  to  be  applicable  to  as  many  individuals  as  pos- 
sible. 

I  am  assuming,  I  think  with  Mr.  Pepper,  that  criticism  aims  to 
make  us  well  acquainted  with  particular  works,  to  bring  us  close  to 
them  so  that  we  not  only  recognize  what  they  may  have  in  common 
with  other  works,  but  perceive  also  what  is  not  duplicated  anywhere, 
unless  it  be  in  perfect  copies.  I  do  not  claim  that  all  criticism  has 
this  function,  but  for  the  present  I  refer  to  the  kind  that  does  have 
it.  And  this  kind  of  criticism  does  seem  to  care  only  or  chiefly  about 
the  individual  and  to  be  indifferent  to  the  type.  And  if  the  essence 
of  science  is  to  be  capable  of  statement  in  laws  which  are  not  imagi- 
nary universals,  but  which  convey  a  knowledge  of  certain  constant 
and  repeating  details  of  nature,  criticism  evidently  can  not  be  scien- 
tific. 

We  can  describe  the  nature  of  horses,  and  the  nature  of  tuber- 
culosis, but  what  exists  are  individual  horses  and  individual  sick 
people.  This,  I  suppose,  is  the  natural  subject  matter  of  any  science 
of  horses  or  science  of  medicine.  One  horse  is,  to  be  sure,  like  another 
and  yet  just  those  respects  in  which  one  horse  is  not  like  another 
i ' '  A  Suggestion  Regarding  Esthetics, ' '  this  JOUBNAL. 


120  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

may  be  what  "makes  all  the  difference."  In  ethics  rules  are  im- 
portant, but  we  say  often  that  a  case  must  be  judged  on  its  own 
merits.  A  science  of  ethics,  however,  must  consist  of  rules  or  other 
general  statements.  Yet,  surely,  a  science  of  ethics  exists,  or  ought 
to  exist,  for  the  sake  of  its  natural  subject  matter,  just  those  in- 
dividual cases  that  may  show  all  manner  of  departure  from  type  or 
complication  of  type. 

The  phraseology  of  universals  is  no  less  essential  to  philosophy 
than  it  is  to  science  (admitting,  for  the  moment,  a  difference).  But 
what  is  passed  over  is  ignored  just  because  it  is  not  found  in  all 
members  of  the  type;  and  how  significant  or  valuable  this  may  be  in 
concrete  human  experience  can  be  decided  only  by  some  other  man- 
ner of  approach.  Any  method,  then,  which  aims  at  propositions  in- 
tended to  be  true  of  indefinitely  many  individuals  mast  leave  un- 
noticed more  or  less  of  the  actual  content  which  another  method 
concerned  with  one  thing  at  a  time  might  pay  full  attention  to.  And 
a  science  of  esthetics,  if  a  science  at  all,  would  be  like  other  science 
in  this  respect. 

Is,  then,  a  science  of  esthetics  impossible?  Candidly,  I  don't 
know,  but  I  suspect  it  is ;  or,  perhaps,  I  would  prefer  to  say  that  we 
already  have  it  in  the  only  sense  that  is  worth  insisting  upon.  For 
the  sake  of  what  fruits  would  a  science  of  esthetics  exist?  What  is 
its  natural  subject  matter?  Again  I  am  not  sure  that  I  know,  or 
rather  I  would  say  that  it  may  have  various  fruits  and  be  about  a 
variety  of  things.  That  is  a  verbal  matter;  and  provided  the  ques- 
tions studied  are  not  artificial  questions,  and  the  discussions  not 
confused  by  misunderstanding,  it  is  a  matter  of  no  great  conse- 
quence. If,  however,  the  study  of  esthetics  is  to  lead  us  to  esthetic 
education,  to  experience  marked  by  the  possession  of  fine  and  organ- 
ized esthetic  values,  and  the  constant  activity  of  trained  and  discrimi- 
nating senses,  its  purpose  is  not  to  lead  us  to  something  scientific 
in  the  sense  above  indicated,  but  to  the  unique  individual,  to  some- 
thing not  defined  but  perceived. 

What  escapes  definition  and  coherent  description  in  any  work  of 
art  is  precisely  what  is  unique,  interesting,  and  possibly  most  valu- 
able. A  work  that  has  none  of  this  is  "academic";  it  embodies  the 
rules  and  nothing  else.  We  might  propose  as  a  definition  of  the 
academic :  That  which  is  made  according  to  a  rule — where  the  rule  is 
more  obeyed  than  used.  Of  course,  a  science  of  esthetics  may  aim 
to  give  us  the  academic,  and  perhaps  it  can  not  do  anything  else, 
unless  we  consider  that  it  should  be  a  body  of  information  useful 
in  producing  esthetically  valuable  objects.  But  such  objects  are. 
of  course,  individual,  and  a  great  deal  of  technical,  scientific  knowl- 
edge is  required  for  their  production.  Consider  what  an  architect 


ESTHETIC  VALVES  121 

needs  to  know,  or  a  capable  composer.  A  vast  amount  of  science  is 
necessary  that  the  world  may  contain  what  we  call  works  of  art.  It 
does  not  occur  to  anyone  to  say  that  this  knowledge  constitutes  a 
science  of  esthethics,  but,  after  all,  why  should  we  not  say  so?  It 
is,  at  least,  the  effective  knowledge  that  is  indispensable  if  what  we 
call  art  is  to  be  systematically  created. 

And  now  I  come  to  Mr.  Pepper's  "suggestion,"  viz.,  that  the 
esthetic  object  as  such  is  one  that  is  liked  without  reference  to  any 
utility  and,  perhaps,  in  spite  of  it.  As  Mr.  Pepper  rightly  says,  the 
contrast  between  "intrinsic"  value  and  valuable  instrumentality,  or 
to  use  an  old  and  honest  pair  of  terms,  between  beauty  and  use,  is 
one  of  the  commonplaces  of  the  subject.  But  we  have  not  yet  seemed 
to  get  anywhere  from  this  point  of  departure.  If  the  distinction  is 
to  bear  any  fruit,  it  must  be  interpreted. 

In  this  conceptual  formulation,  the  beautiful  and  the  useful  are 
very  sharply  discriminated,  and  if  one  is  still  at  the  dialectical  stage, 
it  may  seem  that  beauty  and  use  must  be  separated  in  fact  as  they 
are  in  definition.  The  experience  of  so  many  of  us  in  finding  art  only 
in  museums  is  very  misleading.  Many,  at  least,  of  the  treasures  of 
the  great  galleries  were  produced  to  be  a  part,  and  perhaps  a  very 
important  part  of  a  church.  An  altar  piece,  on  the  altar  where  mass 
is  said,  may  or  may  not  be  beautiful,  but  while  in  its  original  posi- 
tion it  is  preeminently  "useful"  ;  subsequently  removed  to  a  mu- 
seum, its  utility  is  lost  and  its  beauty  and  lack  of  use  characterize 
what  is  now  classified  as  a  work  of  art.  Surely  the  problem  of  our 
day  is  how  to  overcome  the  separation — how  to  promote  a  demand 
that  utilities  shall  be  appropriately  esthetic,  and  how  to  make  esthe- 
tic value  pervade  common  things  and  their  use,  not  artificially  and 
self-consciously,  but  simply  and  spontaneously.  What  knowledge 
is  it  that  will  help  us  to  do  this  ?  I  can  not  think  it  is  any  science  of 
esthetics  as  we  are  inclined  to  use  that  word,  but  also,  I  repeat,  I 
can  not  see  why  we  should  not  call  esthetic  science  all  that  science 
that  an  artist  in  one  field  or  another  must  have  if  his  genius  is  to 
have  tools  to  work  with.  The  same  science  may  be  used  for  other 
ends,  but  what  of  it? 

Thus  far,  I  have  spoken  as  though  in  esthetics  one  were  always 
dealing  with  art.  That  is  as  false  as  anything  can  be.  I  suppose  a 
new  wire  fence  is  usually  a  thing  of  esthetic  delight  to  the  farmer 
who  has  just  set  it  up.  A  good  cow,  a  strong  horse,  a  favorite  tennis 
racquet,  are  likely  to  be  objects  of  esthetic  affection.  I  hope  I  may 
be  pardoned  for  suggesting  again  2  a  translation  of  the  beauty-utility 
distinction  into  slightly  different  terms. 

2  Cf.  Some  passages  in  an  article  entitled  ' '  Value  and  Causality, ' '  this 
JOURNAL,  Vol.  15,  No.  4,  p.  85. 


122  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Utility  considers  effects  to  be  produced;  it,  therefore,  envisages 
the  future.  A  type  of  value  that  is  quite  independent  of  conse- 
quences will  presumably  be  an  interest  in  a  present;  witness  the 
eloquent  conclusion  of  Pater's  fine  book,  The  Renaissance.  The 
present  and  the  future  are  both  objects  of  concern,  and  the  future  is 
something  to  be  concerned  about,  because,  sooner  or  later,  it  will 
not  be  future  any  longer  but  present,  and  life  or  experience  is  always 
in  a  present.  If  the  present  is  always  merely  a  scaffolding  for  the 
future,  if  it  never  has  any  value  of  its  own,  life  can  not  be  said  to 
have  much  success.  Let  the  success  of  the  present  be  all  in  dreams 
of  the  future — that  is  indeed  often  the  noblest  and  happiest  pres- 
ent— but  all  the  present  moments  of  any  man  make  up  all  of  that 
man's  life.  If  it  were  not  for  time  and  the  future,  I  do  not  see  how 
there  could  be  any  such  thing  as  consequences  or  instrumentality  in 
the  natural  sense.  From  this  point  of  view,  all  values  of  the  present 
are  esthetic  values  whether  they  pertain  to  works  of  art  or  to  any- 
thing else,  and  all  values  actually  attained  are  attained  in  a  present. 

The  translation  of  the  beauty  and  use  contrast  into  the  temporal 
contrast  of  present  and  future  is  not  advanced  here  as  of  any  im- 
portance, least  of  all  as  of  any  importance  for  esthetics;  but  it  may 
be  interesting  nevertheless.  Of  that  the  reader  must  judge;  he 
should  remember,  too,  that  such  contrasts  are  likely  to  be  discrimina- 
tions in  analysis  and  not  separations  in  fact.  Whether  or  not  the 
temporal  contrast  is  significant  for  esthetics,  it  is  fundamental  in 
morals,  in  life.  The  puritan  moralist  despises  the  lover  of  beauty 
because  he  lives  too  much  in  a  present.  The  lover  of  beauty  dislikes 
the  moralist  who  impoverishes  life  by  postponing  the  enjoyment  of 
its  fruits.  To  each  of  these  the  word  ' '  good ' '  has  a  different  meaning. 
To  a  certain  extent  we  could  translate  beauty  and  use  into  another 
contrast,  the  individual  and  the  group.  No  such  translation  should 
be  overworked  or  regarded  as  absolute,  but  with  this  proviso  any  such 
translation,  if  based  upon  empirical  relations,  is  likely  to  clarify 
more  or  less. 

Why  should  a  distinction  that  has  proved  so  barren  as  the  dis- 
tinction of  the  useful  and  the  valuable  useless  nevertheless  persist? 
While  the  distinction  as  phrased  may  be  too  much  in  terms  of  a  logi- 
cal antithesis,  it  may  yet  represent  something  that  is  both  real  and 
important.  I  think  Mr.  Pepper  is  right  in  indicating  the  distinction 
as  important,  not  as  a  dialectical  major  premise,  but  as  a  point  of  de- 
parture, as  something  to  interpret  in  terms  of  relevant  experience. 
So  much  tragedy  in  life  is  produced  by  esthetic  appeals  to  the  soul, 
and  so  much  dignity  by  other  esthetic  appeals.  Fruits  ripen,  if  you 
like,  in  the  future  but  they  are  enjoyed  in  the  present;  and  when 
they  belong  to  what  we  call  the  past,  it  is  the  present  that  they 


ESTHETIC  VALUES  123 

brighten  or  stain,  and  the  future  that  they  influence.  And  when 
we  say  they  influence  the  future,  we  mean  that  they  influence  a 
present  yet  to  come.  As  I  have  said  the  temporal  contrast  may  not 
be  very  relevant,  if  terms  are  used  absolutely,  but  it  is  a  distinction 
that  all  empirical  moralists  and  all  directors  of  conduct  must,  one 
may  suppose,  have  to  make  continually. 

And  now,  if  I  seem  to  abandon  what  I  have  so  labored  to  express, 
that,  perhaps,  only  illustrates  my  thesis  that  life  is  continuous  and 
one  moment  plays  into  another,  but  that  one  moment  may  be  dis- 
tinguished from  another.  Interpret  the  distinction  of  beauty  and  use 
in  some  other  way;  interpret  it  in  as  many  ways  as  possible,  since 
any  interpretation  is  the  noticing  of  some  feature  or  some  relation; 
in  what  is  subtle  and  interesting. 

In  nature  no  factor  is  more  important  than  the  factor  of  timer 
but  of  this  logic  takes  hardly  any  account;  and  though  time  is  an 
important  term  in  physics,  it  is  so  in  a  sense  very  different  from  that 
which  gives  it  such  a  role  in  the  literature  of  human  feeling.  The 
arithmetic  of  life  insurance  companies  brings  us  closer  to  what  time 
means  to  those  that  live  and  grow  old  and  to  those  that  write  his- 
tory; to  those,  too,  who  have  inherited  the  patrimony  our  ancestors 
achieved. 

For,  in  any  case,  the  depth  and  solidity  of  the  esthetic  factor  in 
a  person's  life  depend  very  much  upon  what  kind  of  a  world  he  is 
permitted  to  live  in,  depend,  that  is,  greatly  upon  the  degree  to- 
which  normal  and  sharable  esthetic  values  have  been  brought  into  a 
heritage  for  him  or  her  by  the  past.  A  world  rich  in  what  is  digni- 
fied, simple  and  beautiful  may  not  be  more  "useful"  than  another 
in  the  usual  sense  of  that  now  somewhat  unhappy  word,  but  it  is  a 
great  deal  better.  And  in  the  larger  sense  of  the  word,  and  the  truer 
one,  it  is  supremely  useful,  since  it  perpetuates  itself.  To  possess 
this  patrimony  and  to  transmit  it  with  the  addition  of  what  we  have 
made  it  yield,  not  as  a  dead  past  but  as  something  that  binds  one 
generation  to  another  and  makes  a  single  life  out  of  the  lives  of  many 
men  or  of  many  nations,  to  hold  together  a  community  of  the  spirit, 
not  merely  in  space  but  in  time,  seems  to  me  a  large  part  of  what 
we  may  reasonably  call  our  esthetic  responsibility,  something  that 
the  study  of  esthetics  ought  to  encourage  and  promote. 

WENDELL  T. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


124  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

IMMEDIATE  INFERENCE  AND  THE  DISTRIBUTION 
OF  TERMS 

IN  tlu-  interpretation  of  exclusive  and  exceptive  propositions 
there  is  a  difficulty  pertinent  to  the  discussion  carried  on  in 
this  JOURNAL1  by  Professor  Toohey  and  Professor  Dotterer  as  to 
the  distribution  of  the  predicate  in  the  partial  inverse  of  affirma- 
tive propositions,  and  as  to  "immediate  inference"  and  the  distri- 
bution of  terms  in  general. 

The  exceptive  proposition  offers  a  privileged  example  of  how, 
in  an  actual  situation  within  a  limited  universe  of  discourse,  the 
]>;u-tial  inverse  of  a  true  proposition  may  well  assert  what  is  not 
true.  All  but  8  is  P,  we  are  told,  is  correctly  expressed  by  the  A 
proposition,  All  non-8  is  P;  and  from  this  is  correctly  derived 
Some  S  is- not  P.  It  is  agreed  that  we  have  no  right  to  say  No  8 
is  P-  and  examination  of  the  meaning  of  All  but  8  is  P  will  con- 
vince, I  believe,  that  strictly  taken  it  need  not  express  the  situation 
from  which  alone  Some  8  is-not  P  is  justified.  When  Francis  I 
wrote  home  "All  is  lost  but  honor,"  he  undoubtedly  meant  that 
honor  was  not  lost ;  and  in  general  we  should  rightly  hold  the  man 
who  used  exceptives  to  suggest  what  he  knew  to  be  untrue  as  at 
least  not  a  model  of  truthfulness.  Yet  it  must  be  admitted  that, 
if  Francis  had  lost  honor  as  well  as  all  else  but  preferred  not  to 
say  so,  he  would  have  told,  not  the  whole  truth  to  be  sure,  yet  not 
strictly  an  untruth;  inasmuch  as  he  had  made  no  assertion  about 
honor  but  had  merely  held  it  apart  from  the  assertion  he  did  make. 
And  in  fact,  our  exceptives  frequently  arise  simply  from  ignorance 
which  is  properly  recognized  in  the  limitation  of  our  judgment, 
or  from  a  courteous,  discreet,  kindly,  timid,  or  malicious  reserva- 
tion of  statement.  The  conventional  "present  company  excepted" 
is  notoriously  untrustworthy  in  any  positive  implication.  Or  let 
us  agree  that  any  triangle  must  be  scalene,  isosceles,  or  equilateral. 
Then  to  say  "scalene  triangles"  is  to  say  "all  triangles  except 

celes  and  equilateral  triangles."  And  scalene  triangles  have 
three  sides.  Substituting  the  equivalent  term,  we  may  say  "All 
triangles  except  isoceles  and  equilateral  triangles  have  three  sides" 
— and,  if  we  had  to  discover  the  number  of  sides  of  triangles  by 
inspection,  we  might  well,  after  an  examination  only  of  scalene 
triangles,  make  this  assertion ;  but  it  would  be  none  the  less  false  to 
say  that  some  isosceles  or  equilateral  triangles  do  not  have  three 
sides.  In  short,  the  exceptive  proposition  is  a  statement  which  is 
said  to  be  correctly  represented  by  a  proposition  from  which  is 
correctly  derived  a  proposition  which  is  not  necessarily  implied 
i  Vol.  XVII,  pp.  519-522;  Vol.  XVIII,  pp.  320-326. 


INFERENCE  AND  DISTRIBUTION  125 

by  the  original  statement.  It  appears,  then,  that  either  All  non-8 
is  P  does  not  adequately  and  simply  express  the  import  of  All  but 
8  is  P  OT  the  process  of  inversion  is  in  some  cases  illicit. 

The  case  of  the  exclusive  proposition  is  more  illuminating; 
since  here  the  untruth,  though  of  precisely  similar  nature,  may  be 
taken  as  not  the  result  of  inversion,  and  in  any  case  does  not  in- 
volve the  inversion  of  an  affirmative  proposition.  None  but  8  is  P 
is  ordinarily  represented,  for  syllogistic  purposes,  by  All  P  is  8; 
and  the  converse  of  this  is  Some  8  is  P.  If  it  be  said  that  the  ex- 
clusive is  more  properly  represented  by  No  non-8  is  P,  then  All  P 
is  8  is  the  obverted  converse,  Some  8  is  P  the  partial  inverse.  But 
here  it  is  the  partial  inverse  of  an  E  proposition,  and  there  is  no 
infraction  of  the  rules  of  distribution.  The  possible  falsehood, 
however,  remains  as  with  exceptives ;  for  Some  8  is  P  is  frequently 
in  actual  cases  not  true.  Admittedly  we  have  no  right  to  say  All 
8  is  P ;  and  since  no  assertion  is  made  of  8,  wherein  do  we  get  the 
right  to  speak  even  of  a  part  of  8  ?  Surely  ' '  No  admittance  except 
on  business"  ordinarily  implies  that  some  of  those  intent  on  busi- 
ness are  admitted,  but  since  other  rules  unnamed  or  other  existing 
circumstances  may  well  exclude  all  actual  persons  applying,  we  can 
not  with  strict  assurance  say  that  anyone  is  admitted.  And  this 
is  not  mere  abstract  quibbling,  for  the  case  is  often  actual  because 
of  ignorance,  discretion,  or  the  mere  inadvisability  of  including 
all  conditions  in  one  proposition.  I  may  offer  a  college  course 
which  is  truly  described  as  elective  (none  but  those  who  elect  it 
take  it),  and  as  open  only  to  seniors  (none  but  seniors  take  it) ; 
and  if  there  is  no  senior,  or  no  one  who  desires  it,  or  no  senior 
who  desires  it,  it  will  be  false  to  say  that  some  who  elect  it  take  it  or 
that  some  seniors  take  it.  It  might  be  quite  true  that  only  a  mathe- 
matical genius  can  square  the  circle;  it  is  certainly  not  true  that 
some  mathematical  geniuses  can  square  the  circle.  In  short,  it 
appears  that  either  No  non-8  is  P  is  not  a  perfect  expression  for 
None  but  8  is  P,  or  there  is  a  loss  of  truth  in  obtaining  the  obverted 
converse  of  E  (here,  All  P  is  8),  or  there  is  a  loss  in  obtaining  the 
converse  of  A  (here,  Some  8  is  P). 

In  general  it  appeal's  that  by  the  use  of  accepted  methods  of 
interpretation  we  may  from  everyday  assertions  obtain  propositions 
which  are  seen  to  be  untrue  or  possibly  untrue  when  referred  to 
the  actual  situation  from  which  the  original  assertion  sprang  and 
of  which  the  original  assertion  is  true.  The  error  at  times  shows 
as  a  formal  violation  of  the  rule  against  going  from  an  undistrib- 
uted to  a  distributed  term;  but  is  broader  and  apparently  not  to 
be  solved  by  a  solution  of  the  difficulty  about  distribution,  since  it 
appears  where  there  is  no  evidence  of  that  difficulty.  It  may 


126  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

further  be  noted  that,  inasmuch  as  the  error  is  real,  it  directly 
impugns  not  the  rule  of  distribution  but  the  processes  wherein  that 
rule  fails. 

Now  Dr.  Keynes,  whose  doctrine  as  to  the  distribution  of  the 
predicate  in  the  partial  inverse  of  an  A  proposition  Professor  Dot- 
terer  seeks  to  amend  and  Professor  Toohey  rejects,  seems  to  me 
at  least  to  point  the  way  to  the  solution  of  the  problem,  though 
not  in  his  direct  treatment  of  "validity  of  inversion"  in  the  fourth 
edition  of  his  Formal  Logic.  His  discussion  in  the  third  edition 
seems  to  me  the  better,  and  the  real  clue  to  the  larger  problem  is  af- 
forded by  a  footnote  at  the  beginning  of  the  chapter  on  Immediate 
Inference.2  The  usually  accepted  explanation  is  that  of  the  fourth 
edition,  according  to  which  in  inversion  of  All  8  is  P  we  tacitly 
assume  the  premise  Some  things  are  not  P.  "The  conclusion,  Some 
not-S  is  not  P,  may  accordingly  be  regarded  as  based  on  this 
premise  combined  with  the  explicit  premise  All  S  is  P;  and  it  will 
be  observed  that,  in  the  additional  premise,  P  is  distributed."* 
Now  the  introduction  of  this  assumed  premise  does  seem  to  pro- 
vide a  proper  distribution  for  P;  yet,  taken  strictly,  how  does  it 
act  as  premise?  It  can  not  be  combined  with  the  other  premise 
in  any  possible  syllogistic  form  to  give  the  required  conclusion. 
And  if  the  mere  presence  of  a  distributed  term  in  an  assumed 
proposition  gives  us  the  right  to  distribute  that  term  in  the  series 
of  transformations  of  the  proposition  with  which  we  are  working, 
it  gives  us  decidedly  too  much;  for  it  would  justify  any  distribu- 
tion of  that  term  and  merely  abrogate  the  rule  of  distribution  alto- 
gether. We  could  go  simply  from  All  S  is  P  to  All  P  is  8.  Professor 
Dotterer  is  quite  right  in  pointing  out  that  the  distribution  of  a 
term  is  not  an  absolute  matter,  but  is  relative  to  some  other  term 
or  terms.  Distribution  is  a  property  of  terms  "in  syntax."  We 
can  not  hunt  around  for  any  proposition  in  which  a  certain  term 
is  distributed,  and  then  proceed  blithely  to  distribute  it  in  some 
other  series  of  transformations.  On  the  other  hand  Professor 
Toohey  is  quite  right  in  maintaining  that  to  make  a  term  distrib- 
uted or  undistributed  relatively  to  some  one  other  term  and  to 
deny  any  pertinency  to  this  distribution  elsewhere  is  equally  to 
take  all  value  from  distribution.  Within  any  series  of  transforma- 
tions of  a  proposition  or  within  any  true  syllogistic  series  (proposi- 
tions connected  by  competent  middle  terms),  we  have  the  right  to 
speak  of  distribution  or  lack  of  distribution  simply ;  but  not  as  be- 
tween unconnected  propositions.  A  distributed  term,  that  is,  is 
distributed  with  regard  to  the  other  term  in  its  proposition  and  to 

»  Keynee:  Formal  Logic,  4th  ed.,  p.  126,  n.  1;  3d  ed.,  p.  93,  n.  1. 
*  Ibid.,  4th  ed.,  pp.  139  ff. 


INFERENCE  AND  DISTRIBUTION  127 

the  other  terms  in  other  propositions  connected  therewith  by  distrib- 
uted middle  terms.  An  undistributed  term  is  undistributed  with 
regard  to  the  other  term  in  its  proposition  and  to  the  other  terms 
in  other  propositions  connected  therewith  by  middle  terms,  distrib- 
uted or  undistributed. 

But  this  is  not  all.  With  regard  to  its  own  contradictory,  and 
to  at  least  some  part  of  the  contradictory  of  the  other  term  in  its 
proposition  if  that  proposition  is  universal,  any  term  is  always 
distributed.  For  by  the  principle  of  contradiction  the  contradic- 
tory of  any  term  is  excluded  from  the  whole  of  that  term;  and, 
since  in  all  universal  propositions  at  least  some  portion  of  the  ex- 
tension of  the  contradictory  of  the  other  term  must  coincide  with 
some  portion  of  that  of  the  contradictory  of  the  term  in  question, 
with  regard  to  at  least  that  portion  of  the  contradictory  of  the 
other  term  the  term  in  question  will  be  distributed.  But,  of  course, 
this  is  true  only  if  there  are  contradictories  to  these  terms.  For  if 
there  be  no  contradictory  to  the  term  in  question,  then  it  will  not 
necessarily  be  distributed  with  regard  to  any  portion  of  the  con- 
tradictory of  the  other  term.  And  if  there  be  no  contradictory  to 
the  other  term,  it  would  be  meaningless  to  assert  distribution  with 
regard  to  some  portion  of  it.  And  this  is  why  the  assumption  of 
the  existence  of  the  contradictory  of  the  original  predicate  vali- 
dates the  partial  inverse:  not  that  we  manufacture  any  premise 
therefrom,  but  that,  if  that  contradictory  exist,  the  term  by  its 
very  nature  will  always  be  distributed  with  regard  to  it ;  and  that 
obviously  in  the  A  proposition  with  which  we  start,  if  the  contra- 
dictory of  the  predicate  exist,  then  the  subject  must  have  a  con- 
tradictory which  in  some  part  must  coincide  with  the  contradictory 
of  the  predicate;  and  with  regard  to  that  part  the  predicate  will 
always  be  distributed — as  it  were  by  right  of  eminent  domain.  Now 
abstractly  a  contradictory  can  be  made  to  any  term;  but  actually, 
of  course,  we  may  have  to  deal  with  an  all-inclusive  genus,  either 
absolutely  or  as  an  exhaustive  species  within  some  explicitly  limited 
universe  of  discourse.  The  case,  then,  in  the  matter  of  the  partial 
inverse  is  this.  The  explanation  does  not  lie  in  any  premise,  but 
does  lie  in  the  assumption  of  the  existence  of  the  contradictory  of 
the  original  predicate.  For  if  that  contradictory  exist,  then  the 
predicate,  being  always  distributed  with  regard  to  it,  must  also  be 
distributed  with  regard  to  whatever  portion  of  the  contradictory 
of  the  original  subject  coincides  with  it;  and  somewhere  within 
the  same  universe  these  two  infinites  must  at  least  partially  coin- 
cide. We  have  thus  the  right  to  say  Some  not-S  is  not  P,  since  P 
must  be  distributed  with  regard  to  some  portion  of  not-S.  But  actu- 
ally we  may  have  as  predicate  an  exhaustive  species  which  allows  no 


128  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

existing  contradictory,  as  if  we  say  "All  is  lost  but  honor"  when 
really  there  is  nothing  not  lost.  In  such  a  case,  going  from  "All 
things  other  than  honor  are  lost"  to  "Some  honor  is  not  lost,"  we  do 
go  from  a  lack  of  distribution  to  distribution,  and  from  truth  to 
falsehood. 

Now  this  is  but  an  instance  of  the  general  principle  given  first 
by  Dr.  Keynes  in  the  footnote  already  referred  to.  "We  proceed 
on  the  assumption  that  each  class  represented  by  a  simple  term 
exists  in  the  universe  of  discourse,  while  at  the  same  time  it  does 
not  exhaust  that  universe.  This  assumption  appears  always  to  have 
been  made  implicitly  in  the  traditional  treatment  of  logic." 

It  is  that  assumption,  together  with  the  acceptance  of  the  logic- 
ally prior  principle  of  contradiction  which  necessitates  the  distri- 
bution of  any  term  relatively  to  its  contradictory,  and  together 
with  the  nature  of  the  relations  expressed  in  categorical  proposi- 
tions which  through  the  principles  of  contradiction  and  excluded 
middle  necessitates  the  coincidence  of  at  least  part  of  the  con- 
tradictory of  one  term  with  at  least  part  of  the  contradictory  of 
the  other  term  in  all  universal  propositions,  which  validates  the 
partial  inverse  of  the  universal  affirmative  proposition.  And  it 
is  that  assumption  which  is  apt  to  give  rise  to  error  when  the  pro- 
cedures based  thereupon  are  applied  to  actual  situations  not  con- 
forming thereto;  not  only  in  the  partial  inverse  of  A,  but,  as  we 
have  seen  with  exclusive  propositions,  in  the  partial  inverse  of  E, 
where  the  lack  of  conformity  is  in  the  assumption  of  the  existence 
of  the  original  predicate  or  of  the  contradictory  of  the  subject; 
and,  indeed,  in  other  interpretations,  even,  conceivably,  in  so  direct 
a  one  as  limited  conversion  or  simple  conversion  or  simple  obver- 
sion.  The  formal  violation  of  the  rule  as  to  distribution  is  apparent 
in  one  case  only,  not  because  of  any  peculiar  invalidity  of  the  in- 
version of  A  propositions,  but  simply  because  for  other  reasons  the 
partial  inverse  of  A  is  the  only  case  in  which  an  originally  undis- 
tributed term  reappears  distributed  with  regard  to  the  contradic- 
tory of  the  other  term ;  but  there  are  several  in  which  the  contradic- 
tory of  an  originally  undistributed  term  is  distributed.  And 
whence  comes  this  right?  From  the  fact,  of  course,  that  the  con- 
tradictory of  a  term  is  necessarily  distributed  with  regard  to  that 
term,  and  hence,  in  affirmative  propositions,  with  regard  also  to  at 
least  part  of  the  other  term,  and,  in  negative  propositions,  with 
regard  to  at  least  part  of  the  contradictory  of  the  other  term.  It 
is  thus  (with  one  exception,  the  full  contrapositive,  which  will  be 
noticed  presently)  that  in  the  scheme  of  eduction  contradictories 
will  be  found  distributed.  In  general:  Any  term  is  distributed 
with  regard  to  its  contradictory  and  its  contradictory  with  regard 


INFERENCE  AND  DISTRIBUTION         ,          129 

to  it.  When  the  term  is  put  into  a  proposition,  further  results 
follow  from  this.  In  all  universal  propositions,  the  term  will  be 
distributed  with  regard  to  at  least  part  of  the  contradictory  of  the 
other  term.  If  the  universal  be  affirmative,  the  subject  will  be 
distributed  with  regard  to  the  whole  of  the  contradictory  of  the 
predicate.  In  all  affirmative  propositions,  the  contradictory  of  the 
term  will  be  distributed  with  regard  to  at  least  part  of  the  other 
term.  If  the  affirmative  be  universal,  the  contradictory  of  the 
predicate  will  be  distributed  with  regard  to  the  whole  of  the  sub- 
ject and  will  further  be  distributed  with  regard  to  at  least  part 
of  the  contradictory  of  the  subject.  (Cf.  the  full  contrapositive, 
All  not-P  is  not-S.)  In  all  negative  propositions,  the  contradictory 
of  the  term  will  be  distributed  with  regard  to  at  least  part  of  the 
contradictory  of  the  other  term.  An  examination  of  the  table  of 
results  of  obversion  and  conversion  will  substantiate  these  a  priori 
relations.  In  fact  they  are  tacitly  assumed  in  the  principles  of 
obversion  and  conversion,  and,  having  once  accepted  these  princi- 
ples, we  need  not,  so  long  as  we  correctly  apply  them,  bother  about 
particular  distributions.  But  the  whole  structure  rests  upon  the 
assumption  that  the  terms  have  existence  within  the  same  universe 
of  discourse  and  that  neither  exhausts  that  universe. 

The  really  important  question,  then,  is  as  to  the  justification 
for  this  assumption.  This  is  not  the  place  for  a  complete  discus- 
sion of  so  profoundly  reaching  a  question,  but  a  few  suggestions 
present  themselves. 

In  the  first  place,  it  must  be  admitted  that  the  lack  of  con- 
formity is  real  and  not  negligible.  In  the  fluency  of  our  state- 
ments, we  make  many  assertions  taken  as  true  relevant  to  a  situa- 
tion which  rejects  some  formal  transformations  of  those  assertions. 
And  it  must  be  admitted  that  obversion  and  conversion  need  some 
more  basic  justification  than  a  let-it-be-so.  Yet  this  is  not  neces- 
sarily a  condemnation  of  immediate  inference  nor  an  indictment 
of  formal  logic.  We  can  not  hope  always  to  find  a  ready  confor- 
mity between  usage  and  principle.  If  logic  insists  on  becoming 
complicated,  it  is  therein  not  different  from  other  sciences  which 
attempt  to  conform  to  the  wanton  wiles  of  the  actual.  Much  of  the 
contemporary  complaint  against  logic  is  really  a  complaint  against 
the  waywardness  of  language — the  complaint  that  people  refuse 
(for  which,  on  other  grounds,  we  owe  thanks)  to  confine  the  opu- 
lence of  expression  to  the  pigeonholes  of  logicians.  The  formality 
of  logic  is  of  meaning,  not  of  word;  and  all  interpretation  moves 
under  the  threat  of  material  fallacy,  whose  generic  nature  is  equiv- 
ocation. Logic  may  well  be  complete  and  valid,  despite  the  diffi- 
culties which  expression  makes  for  diagnosis. 


130  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

The  assumption  that  subject  and  predicate  belong  to  the  same 
universe  of  discourse  we  may  readily  allow  as  just.  It  flows  from 
the  very  nature  of  judgment.  It  is  true,  of  course,  that  sometimes, 
when  we  come  to  take  contradictories  for  the  purposes  of  obvereion, 
we  fall  into  error  through  an  unwarranted  limitation  of  one  term 
with  respect  to  the  other ;  but  even  here  the  one  universe  is  part  of 
the  other,  and  the  error  in  extension  is  chargeable  to  faulty  manipu- 
lation on  our  part,  not  to  any  defect  in  judgment.  When,  above,  I 
used  the  illustration  All  equilateral  triangles  have  three  sides;  Some 
non-equilateral  triangles  have  not  three  sides,  it  was  doubtless  appar- 
ent that  a  more  careful  contradictory  for  the  subject  would  have 
avoided  the  falsehood ;  yet  the  illustration  there  was  proper,  for,  if 
both  subject  and  predicate  were  reduced  to  the  limited  universe  tri- 
angles, the  falsehood  would  remain:  All  equilateral  triangles  are 
three-sided  triangles;  Some  non-equilateral  triangles  are  not  three- 
sided  triangles. 

We  may  also,  it  seems,  admit  as  just  and  necessary  the  assump- 
tion that  the  terms  do  not  either  exhaust  the  universe.  This,  how- 
ever, is  a  necessity  not  of  the  essence  of  the  judgment  but  of  the 
essence  of  obversion;  and,  though  obversion — negative  statement — 
is  too  natural  and  proper  a  mode  of  expression  to  be  discarded  or 
seriously  impaired  by  the  chance  of  failure  in  limiting  cases,  we 
must  recognize  the  essential  shortcoming  of  the  process.  In  abso- 
lute statements  the  limiting  case  is  negligible ;  we  do  not  often  deal 
with  completely  exhaustive  genus.  The  pinch  comes  because  our 
actual  statements  so  often  have  to  do  with  artificial,  delimited  uni- 
verses. And  here,  so  long  as  our  assertion  is  of  definite,  positive 
species,  there  is  small  danger;  for,  if  one  of  the  terms  does  exhaust 
the  universe,  we  are  apt  to  have  our  eyes  open  to  it,  or  at  any  rate 
the  derived  statement  will  hide  itself  in  the  decent  obscurity  of  an 
infinite  term.  But  where  our  assertion  begins  with  an  indefinite 
negative,  trouble  arises;  for  that  term  reappears  as  a  definite  and 
positive  term,  and  either  we  know  it  does  not  exist  or,  more  usually, 
we  know  it  does  exist  and  infer  from  it  a  like  existence  for  the  other 
term  which  may  not  exist.  So,  from  All  not-S  is  P,  we  get  the 
inverse  forms  Some  S  is  not  P  and  Some  S  is  not-P;  and,  knowing 
the  actual  existence  of  the  definite  S,  we  ascribe  equal  existence  to 
not-P,  which,  if  P  in  the  first  place  exhausted  the  universe,  has  no 
existence  at  all.  This  is  the  source  of  the  peculiar  liability  of  exclu- 
sive propositions  to  false  interpretation.  Even  the  contrapositives, 
which  enjoy  a  somewhat  privileged  position  as  it  were  because  of  their 
kinship  to  the  denial  of  the  consequent,  are  vulnerable  here. 

If  obversion  lays  itself  open  to  actual  error  because  of  the  assump- 
tion that  the  terms  do  not  exhaust  the  universe,  conversion  runs  foul 


INFERENCE  AND  DISTRIBUTION  131 

of  the  more  primary  assumption  of  the  existence  of  the  terms.  But 
it  may  "be  noted  that  this  assumption  involves  less  than  at  first 
appears,  and  for  affirmative  propositions  at  any  rate  may  be  pretty 
well  justified.  For  it  does  not,  of  course,  necessitate  any  special 
sort  of  existence,  certainly  not  physical  existence,  for  the  terms; 
we  can  deal  validly  with  propositions  concerning  chimeras,  myths, 
abstractions ;  nor,  further,  does  it  necessitate  even  that  the  terms  or 
either  of  them  be  in  the  original  proposition  thought  in  extension 
at  all.  All  we  need  assume  is  that  our  terms  have  some  meaning, 
and  that  whatever  sort  of  existence  is  implied  of  one  can  be  truly 
thought  as  inhering  in  the  other  within  the  same  universe.  And  for 
affirmative  categorical  propositions  this  seems  an  easily  justifiable 
assumption.  If  we  accept  the  commonly  accepted  view  that  affirma- 
tive categoricals  imply  the  denotative  existence  of  their  subjects, 
then,  even  though  the  predicate  be  thought  primarily  in  pure  inten- 
sion, it  must  nevertheless  be  admitted  as  capable  of  extension  at 
least  so  far  as  the  proposition  asserts  coincidence  of  that  intension 
with  the  extension  of  the  subject.  And  if  it  be  maintained  that  in 
any  certain  proposition  both  subject  and  predicate  are  in  pure  inten- 
sion, then  no  difficulty  will  arise,  since  after  conversion  no  different 
logical  being  can  be  asserted  of  either  term  than  in  the  original 
proposition  belonged  to  both.  Two  troubles,  however,  are  found.  In 
the  psychology  of  understanding  propositions,  we  commonly  (and 
correctly)  grasp  the  subject  and  then  infer  of  the  predicate  at  least 
potentially  the  same  sort  of  existence  we  know  the  subject  to  have. 
It  thus  sometimes  happens  that,  beginning  with  a  proposition  the 
subject  of  which  has  a  limited  sort  of  existence  and  the  predicate 
of  which  is  an  attribute  belonging  not  merely  to  the  subject  but  to 
other  subjects  having  much  more  complete  existence,  we  arrive  at 
a  converse  according  to  which  we  are  tempted  to  extend  to  the  new 
predicate  the  full-statured  existence  belonging  to  some  other  part 
of  the  extension  of  the  new  subject.  But  inasmuch  as  the  converse 
of  an  affirmative  is  always  particular,  this  error  is  always  simply 
one  of  presumption  on  our  part,  not  of  illicit  import  in  the  conver- 
sion. The  other  danger  arises  from  the  frequency  with  which  we 
express  what  are  properly  hypothetical  judgments  in  categorical 
form.  Here  the  partiality  of  the  converse  will  not  save  us,  for  the 
reduction  required — the  shift  in  relation  as  we  pass  from  that  of  sub- 
ject to  predicate  to  that  of  predicate  to  subject — is  not  a  matter  of 
quantity,  from  universal  to  particular,  but  is  a  matter  of  modality, 
from  apodeictic  to  problematic.  So  it  is  with  rules,  mandatory  and 
diagnostic.  From  the  legend  No  admittance  except  on  business  I 
know  that  if  someone  is  admitted  he  must  be  on  business.  Now 
perhaps  I  put  this  All  admitted  persons  are  persons  on  business; 


132  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

but  if  I  want  to  make  persons  on  business  the  subject  and  tell  what 
I  know  of  them,  I  ought  to  say,  not  Some  business  persons  are 
admitted,  which  will  almost  certainly  be  taken  to  mean  more  than 
I  know,  but  //  someone  is  a  business  person,  he  may  or  may  not  be 
admitted.  *For  what  I  really  know  about  the  predicate  is  not  that 
at  least  some  of  the  class  are  also  of  the  subject-class,  but  that  at 
least  I  can  not  deny  the  subject  of  any  member  of  the  predicate 
class  as  such.  When  hypotheticals  are  put  as  categoricals,  conver- 
sion, even  by  limitation,  is  an  affirmation  of  the  consequent — and 
inversion  adds  a  denial  of  the  antecedent. 

As  to  negative  propositions,  the  case  is  by  no  means  so  favorable. 
Even  with  respect  to  the  reference  of  the  terms  to  one  universe  there 
may  be  some  hesitation.  I  should  maintain,  however,  that  negatives 
as  well  as  affirmatives  presuppose  some  community  of  relevance  and 
in  more  than  a  barely  formal  sense.  We  may,  to  be  sure,  assent  to 
the  medieval  denial  of  the  triangularity  of  virtue,  but  any  meaning 
which  the  proposition  may  achieve  will  depend  upon  the  possibility 
of  actual  predication  in  some  sense.  To  deny  an  attribute  is  to  imply 
the  significance  of  its  possession.  Our  discussion  of  that  part  of 
the  assumption  which  asserts  that  neither  term  exhausts  the  universe 
will  also  hold  for  negatives  as  well  as  affirmatives;  though  it  may 
be  noted  that  it  is  chiefly  with  negatives  that  actual  usage  belies  the 
assumption,  since  our  mast  frequent  dealings  with  exhaustive  species 
is  when  we  deny  of  some  subject  an  attribute  which  actually  within 
the  limited  universe  in  mind  does  not  exist — whose  contradictory, 
that  is,  is  actually  exhaustive.  Hence,  again,  the  peculiar  vulner- 
ability of  the  exclusive  proposition.  Now  this  exhibits  the  real  diffi- 
culty as  to  negative  propositions:  can  we  assume  that  subject  and 
predicate  have  even  by  implication  the  same  existential  status?  It 
appears  that  one  of  the  commonest  forms  of  negative  judgment  is 
the  denial  with  respect  to  a  subject  thought  in  extension  of  a 
predicate  taken  purely  in  intension  and  actually  having  no  existence 
within  the  universe  of  discourse.  This  lack  of  extensive  implica- 
tion is  not,  however,  so  facile  as  it  seems  at  first  sight ;  for  the  normal 
negative  categorical  directly  and  truthfully  implies  the  coincidence 
with  the  subject  of  some  measure  of  the  contradictory  of  the  predi- 
cate; even  negatives,  as  we  have  seen,  rest  for  their  meaning  upon 
some  community  of  relevance  between  the  terms;  and  the  actual 
errors  in  negatives  are  once  again  a  matter  of  restricted  universes 
or  of  falsely  put  propositions.  Still,  negative  propositions  are 
especially  prolific  in  interpretative  error — error  which  practically 
arises  chiefly  in  this  way :  a  negative  proposition,  having  for  subject 
a  negative,  or  "infinite,"  term  and  for  predicate  a  term  taken  inten- 


INFERENCE  AND  DISTRIBUTION  133 

sively  only,  eventually  becomes  a  particular  affirmative  proposition, 
having  for  subject  the  contradictory  of  the  original  subject  (that 
is,  a  definite  extensive  term)  and  for  predicate  the  original  intensive 
predicate.  The  truth  of  this  depends  upon  the  actual  extensive  exist- 
ence of  the  original  predicate,  an  existence  which  may  be  totally 
lacking.  This  once  again  points  to  the  exclusive  proposition.  Beyond 
this,  practical  error  is  not  apt  to  obtrude;  since  either  the  propo- 
sition remains  negative,  or  the  predicate  falls  into  its  contradictory. 

One  point  already  mentioned  might  be  urged  further  in  defense 
of  the  general  assumption  of  obversion  and  conversion  as  regards 
negative  propositions.  It  may  be  maintained  that  negatives  which 
do  not  comply  with  that  assumption  are  all  properly  not  categorical 
but  hypothetical.  This,  of  course,  is  so  to  define  the  categorical 
proposition  as  to  justify  the  traditional  assumptions  of  "immediate 
inference";  but  it  may  be  supported  on  other  and  prior  grounds, 
and,  though  it  would  mean  a  large  and  highly  undesirable  departure 
from  the  usages  of  language,  it  might  be  none  the  less  necessary  for 
theoretical  rigor. 

It  should  be  noticed  that,  even  if  we  make  up  our  minds  to  this 
step,  we  are  not  saying,  as  has  not  seldom  been  said,  that  logic  con- 
siders propositions  as  taken  in  pure  extension.  This  doctrine  would, 
of  course,  avoid  many  real  difficulties ;  but  it  is  not  only  extremely 
undesirable  because  of  its  divergence  from  usage  but  unnecessary 
for  theory.  We  say  merely  that  a  proposition  which  has  purely 
intensive  import  is  properly  hypothetical,  and,  if  treated  as  cate- 
gorical, may  develop  false  implications.  For  how  may  a  predicate, 
even  of  a  negative  proposition,  be  purely  intensive — with  no  exten- 
sive implication  ?  Only  if  the  subject  is  really  a  condition  not  stated 
as  fulfilled;  only,  that  is,  if  the  obverse  and  converse  relations  be 
problematic,  not  partial  or  contradictory. 

To  revert  to  the  point  of  departure:  it  seems  that  if  we  accept 
the  assumptions  which  Dr.  Keynes  names  and  which  are  implicit  in 
the  procedures  of  ' '  immediate  inference, ' '  those  procedures  are  valid 
and  without  prejudice  to  the  doctrine  of  the  distribution  of  terms, 
subject  or  predicate.  And  if  those  assumptions  be  refused,  the  harm 
done  is  to  "immediate  inference,"  not  to  the  doctrine  of  distribu- 
tion. Nor  does  that  doctrine  itself  involve  the  treatment  of  proposi- 
tions in  pure  extension,  much  less  any  quantification  of  the  predicate. 
It  does,  to  be  sure,  imply  that  all  terms  in  categoricals  have  at  least 
the  possibility  of  application,  extensive  or  denotative;  but  all  we 
need  know  in  order  to  say  a  predicate  is  distributed  is  that,  if  it  be 
taken  as  having  application,  the  assertion  made  covers  the  whole 
extent  thereof.4  The  distribution  of  terms,  that  is,  is  not  a  matter 

*  C/.  Joseph :  An  Introduction  to  Logic,  pp.  218  ff. 


134  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  the  direct  content  of  our  judgment,  but  of  what  must  be  true  of 
the  situation  to  which  our  judgment  is  relevant;  hence  its  basic 
methodological  importance  in  real  inference.  Whether  or  not  we  dis- 
tinguish between  extension  and  denotation,  and  whatever  the  usage 
we  adopt,  are  immaterial  to  this  question  of  distribution.  Whether 
we  be  speaking  of  the  analysis  of  a  genus  into  its  species,  or  of  the 
individual  instances  of  a  species,  our  term  is  distributed  if  our  asser- 
tion is  true  of  all  the  species  or  all  the  instances  there  are.  If  the 
term  be  singular,  then  in  any  assertion  made  of  it  it  will  be  dis- 
tributed, even  though  it  have  no  extension  in  the  sense  of  component 
species,  since  the  assertion  is  taken  as  true  of  the  only  instance  of  the 
term  there  is. 

This  brings  me  back  to  Professor  Toohey  's  paper,  and  especially 
to  one  contention  which  seems  to  me  to  illustrate  a  very  common  and 
harmful  confusion: 

There  is  an  inconsistency  in  the  logician  treating  the  subject  and  predicate 
of  a  proposition  as  classes — an  inconsistency  which  is  masked  by  the  ambiguity 
of  the  words  All  and  Some.  Each  of  these  words  may  have  a  collective  as  weQ 
as  a  distributive  force.  .  .  .  The  rules  of  logic  are  based  on  the  supposition  that 
the  subject  term  is  used  distributively,  or  at  least  that  it  is  not  used  collectively. 
The  words  "  distributed  "  and  "  undistributed  "  can  not  be  applied  to  a  term 
unless  it  is  used  distributively.  In  the  proposition  All  the  angles  of  a  triangle 
are  less  than  two  right  angles,  the  subject  term,  "  angle  of  a  triangle  "  is  dis- 
tributed; for  it  is  used  distributively.  .  .  .  But  in  the  proposition  All  the  angles 
of  a  triangle  are  equal  to  two  right  angles,  no  logician  would  speak  of  the  subject 
term,  "  angle  of  a  triangle,"  as  either  distributed  or  undistributed.  Now  when 
the  subject  and  predicate  of  a  proposition  are  considered  as  classes,  the  proposi- 
tion can  not  convey  any  meaning  unless  both  terms  are  interpreted  in  a  collective 
sense,  and  if  they  are  interpreted  in  this  sense,  the  words  "  distributed  "  and 
' '  undistributed  ' '  can  not  be  applied  to  them,  any  more  than  they  can  be  applied 
to  the  subject  of  the  proposition  All  the  angles  of  a  triangle  are  equal  to  two 
right  angles.  The  words  "  collected  "  and  "  uncolleeted  "  would  not  be  alto- 
gether inappropriate.  If,  then,  the  rules  of  logic  presuppose  that  the  subject 
i?  not  used  collectively,  how  can  they  be  reconciled  with  a  treatment  of  the  propo- 
sition which  imposes  upon  both  subject  and  predicate  a  collective  sense f 

Now  I  am  not  anxious  to  defend  the  treatment  of  terms  purely 
as  classes,  but  I  am  interested  to  find  a  consistent  usage  for  the  words 
"collective"  and  "distributive,"  which  seem  to  me  to  be  involved 
in  an  evident  confusion — especially  in  the  text-books — which  fre- 
quently interferes  in  the  discussion  of  "distributed"  and  "undis- 
tributed," and  which  appears  in  the  passage  just  quoted.  I  give  the 
accepted  doctrine  from  the  text-book  nearest  at  hand : 

A  general  term  is  a  name  which  is  capable  of  being  applied  to  a  whole  group 
of  objects.  ...  A  collective  term,  on  the  other  hand,  is  a  name  applied  to  a 
number  of  individual  things  when  taken  together  and  treated  as  a  whole,  as  a* 
' '  audience, "  an  "  army. "  It  is  important  to  distinguish  carefully  betweem 
general  and  collective  terms.  A  general  term  is  a  name  which  applies  equally  to 


INFERENCE  AND  DISTRIBUTION  135 

each  individual  of  the  group;  or,  in  other  words,  it  is  used  of  the  individuals 
distributively.  A  collective  name  belongs  to  the  whole,  but  not  to  the  separate 
parts  of  the  whole.  Thus  we  say  that  ' '  soldier  "  is  a  general  name,  and  is  used 
distributively  of  each  man  in  a  regiment.  ' '  Regiment, ' '  however,  is  a  collective 
name  for  it  applies  only  to  the  whole  group,  and  not  to  the  individual  soldiers. 
Ambiguity  sometimes  arises  from  the  fact  that  the  English  word  "  all  "  is  used 
in  both  of  these  senses.  .  .  .5 

Fortunately  text-books  are  seldom  critically  read;  but  even  the 
uninferring  sophomore,  quite  correctly  in  exegesis  but  most  falsely 
in  fact,  is  hereby  persuaded  that  that  there  is  a  necessary  alliance 
between  "general  term"  and  "distributive  use,"  that  no  collective 
term  can  be  used  distributively,  and  that  "general"  and  "collective" 
are  contrasted  and  exclusive  categories.  Yet  a  moment's  common- 
sense  will  tell  us  (as,  indeed,  often  the  books  themselves  inconsist- 
ently tell  us)  that  the  same  term  is  frequently  both  general  and 
collective,  that  if  "distributive  use"  is  to  have  any  value  at  all  it 
must  be  applied  to  collectives  which  alone  can  be  used  in  any  other 
way.  And  is  "all"  .  .  .  "used  in  both  of  these  senses"?  Does 
"all"  ever  "apply  equally  to  each  individual  member  of  the  group"? 
The  whole  orthodox  doctrine  is  sheer  confusion  on  the  one  hand; 
between  the  individual  members  of  a  group  of  which  the  term  is  a 
name  and  the  members  of  a  group  of  which  the  term  names  the  mem- 
bers, and  on  the  other  hand  between  distribution  of  meaning  and 
distribution  of  predication.  Let  us  simply  say :  Every  term  is  either 
singular  or  general.  Every  term  is  either  collective  or  not  collective. 
These  distinctions  are  independent  and  knowledge  as  to  whether  a 
term  is  singular  or  general  tells  us  nothing  as  to  whether  it  is  col- 
lective or  not.  Further,  in  regard  to  the  meaning  of  terms  by  them- 
selves :  Every  term,  singular  or  general,  collective  or  not,  distributes 
its  meaning  ("applies  equally  to  each  individual  member  of  the 
group")  to  each  member  of  any  class  of  which  it  may  be  a  member — 
e.g.,  every  table  is  a  table ;  every  Napoleon,  Napoleon ;  every  army, 
army.  And  no  term,  collective  or  not,  distributes  its  meaning  to 
each  member  of  the  class  which  it  is  or  of  which  it  is  the  name — 
e.g.,  no  soldier  is  a  regiment  ("regiment"  never  applies  to  "sol- 
dier") ;  no  angle  of  a  triangle  is  all  the  angles  of  a  triangle.  In 
regard  to  predication  (terms  in  proposition)  :  Any  collective  term 
may  be  used  either  distributively  or  collectively;  i.e.,  the  predicate 
may  be  asserted  of  each  member  of  the  class  or  of  the  class  as  a 
whole.  This  is  simply  not  pertinent  to  non-collectives,  since  only  col- 
lectives  represent  a  class. 

Now  the  ambiguity  of  "all"  is  a  matter  of  predication,  not  of 
•leaning.  We  therefore  agree  that  in  logical  propositions  all  quantity 

°Creighton:  An  Introductory  Logic,  4th  ed.,  pp.  50  ff.  The  treatment  here 
is  decidedly  better  than  in  most  texts. 


136  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

signs  shall  be  used  distributively.  This  is  a  mere  convention  for 
case  in  handling  plural  quantity  signs,  which  would  otherwise,  aa 
collectives,  be  ambiguous.  It  is  not  a  prescript  to  language,  nor  does 
it  prevent  our  accurately  representing  statements  which  come  to  us 
with  "all"  or  "some"  otherwise  used.  And  we  can  not  say,  as  Pro- 
fessor Toohey  and  others  say,  that  "the  rules  of  logic  are  based  on 
the  supposition  that  the  subject  term  is  used  distributively,  or  at 
least  that  it  is  not  used  collectively, ' '  so  long  as  we  separate,  as  Pro- 
fessor Toohey  does,  the  quantity  sign  from  the  subject  term.  Col- 
lectives, singular  and  general,  used  collectively  and  used  distribu- 
tively, are  constantly  found  in  proper  logical  propositions.  Nor  can 
we  say  that  "the  words  'distributed'  and  'undistributed'  can  not 
be  applied  to  a  term  unless  it  is  used  distributively."  Every  "all" 
is  not  to  be  thought  of  as  the  prepositional  quantity  sign  and  excluded 
from  the  subject.  In  Professor  Toohey 's  example,  All  the  angles 
of  a  triangle  are  equal  to  two  right  angles,  "all"  is  not  the  quantity 
sign  but  an  integral  part  of  the  subject  term.  "No  logician  would 
speak  of  the  subject  term,  'angle  of  a  triangle,'  as  distributed  or 
undistributed,"  because  "angle  of  a  triangle"  is  not  the  subject 
term;  but  "all  the  angles  of  a  triangle"  is  the  subject  term,  is  col- 
lective, and  is  distributed.  We  have  the  same  thing  in  Any  regi- 
ment is  made  up  of  soldiers;  where  "regiment"  is  collective,  general, 
used  collectively,  and  distributed.  In  Some  regiments  are  clean- 
shaven we  have  a  general  collective,  used  distributively,  undis- 
tributed; in  The  Fifth  Maryland  Regiment  is  famous,  we  have  a 
singular  collective,  used  collectively,  and  distributed. 

The  most  fundamental  of  Professor  Toohey 's  objections  to  the 
distribution  of  the  predicate  I  can  merely  notice,  inasmuch  as  it  is 
aside  from  the  question  with  which  I  have  here  been  concerned,  and 
as  it  involves  final  questions  of  the  nature  of  logic.  The  objection 
is  "that  the  use  of  the  doctrine  of  the  distribution  of  the  predicate 
involves  a  vicious  circle.  .  .  .  The  logician  .  .  .  first  calls  upon  the 
student's  knowledge  of  the  implication  of  propositions  to  prove  the 
doctrine,  and  then  he  bids  the  student  call  upon  his  knowledge  of 
the  doctrine  in  order  to  find  out  the  implication."  Now  formal  logic, 
truly,  is  not  an  empirical  science;  yet  no  matter  how  a  priori  we 
make  our  construction  of  logical  theory,  it  must  appeal  to  experi- 
ence to  establish  its  appositeness  to  this  world.  And,  moreover,  it 
may  be  doubted  whether  we  could  achieve  a  logic  at  all  did  we  not 
find  for  our  analysis  logical  relations  embodied  in  actual  masses  of 
judgment  which  we  recognize  as  valid ;  and,  at  least  in  the  process  of 
learning  and  teaching,  the  appeal  to  justifying  results  is  not  only  per- 
missible but  necessary.  If  this  be  argument  in  a  circle,  we  shall  have 


BOOK  REVIEWS  137 

to  make  the  best  of  it;  since  it  is  a  circle  from  which  no  human 
thought  can  ever  escape. 

ALBERT  L.  HAMMOND. 
JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

La  Philosophic  moderne  depuis  Bacon  jusqu'd  Leibniz:  Etudes 

historiques.     GASTON  SOBTAIS.     Paris:  Lethielleux.     1920.     Pp. 

x  +  592. 

At  once  ambitious  and  valuable  is  the  series  of  works  which 
Father  Sortais  is  undertaking  in  these  studies  of  the  history  of 
modern  philosophy.  If  succeeding  volumes  are  comparable  to  this 
first  one  in  the  series  in  fullness  and  explicitness  of  treatment,  we 
shall  have  in  the  series  a  veritable  encyclopaedia  of  seventeenth 
century  philosophic  thought — the  century,  of  course,  which  created 
the  atmosphere  and  formulated  the  problems  of  that  epoch  which 
is  called  "modern  philosophy." 

The  first  hundred  pages  of  the  near  six  hundred  forming  the 
volume  are  devoted  to  certain  sixteenth  century  precursors  of 
Francis  Bacon  who  were  concerned  with  questions  of  method  and 
authority — Pierre  Eamus,  Frangois  Sanchez,  Giacomo  Acontio, 
Everard  Digby,  William  Temple,  Nicholas  Hemmingsen — men  who 
were  feeling,  in  various  lines,  after  philosophic  and  scientific  methods 
which  could  lead  them  away  from  the  sterile  scholasticism  of  the 
period  to  a  more  natural  and  direct  investigation  of  nature,  and 
whose  speculative  work  constitutes  an  interesting  parallel  to  the 
series  of  scientific  achievements  which  began  with  the  theories  of 
Copernicus.  With  this  preparation  Father  Sortais  goes  forward  to  a 
study  of  the  topic  of  his  Livre  I,  which  is  I'Empirisme  en  Angleterre 
et  en  France,  devoting  the  remainder  of  the  present  volume  to  a 
study  of  the  life,  work,  and  influence  of  Francis  Bacon.  As  outlined 
in  his  general  plan,  this  is  to  be  followed  by  other  books  devoted  to 
Reactions  que  provoqua  cette  poussee  empirique;  Deisme;  the  Phi- 
losophic du  Droit;  the  Revolution  Cartesienne;  Cartesianisme  en 
France;  Cartesianisme  a  I'etranger;  and  finally,  the  Systemes  plus 
ou  moins  opposes  au  Cartesianisme:  PhUosophie  scolastique,  Scep- 
ticisme,  Pantheisme  de  Spinoza,  Sensualisme  de  Locke,  Dynamisme 
de  Leibniz.  This  is  at  once  an  heroic  and  a  fascinating  programme, 
in  its  very  statement  suggesting  the  dramatic  turn  which  the  au- 
thor sees  in  the  speculative  effort  of  the  century :  first  the  thralldom 
of  empirical  and  mathematical  method,  later  the  uneasy  struggle 
of  the  mind  to  free  itself  from  the  too  exclusive  yoke  of  these 


138  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

powerful  instruments  and  to  discover  truths  to  which  they  might 
lead  but  which  they  could  not  contain. 

The  method  of  the  author  is  itself  an  interesting  commentary 
upon  his  subject  matter.  The  contents  are  organized  as  only  could 
be  by  a  man  trained  in  scholastic  method,  with  all  formal  explicit- 
ness;  but  the  work  itself  is  largely  in  the  nature  of  a  running  ex- 
position of  copious  reader's  notes,  the  exposition  following  the 
materials  with  honest  fidelity.  Taken  in  connection  with  the  full 
and  careful  notes,  sources  and  passages,  this  gives  an  encyclopaedic 
value  to  the  work  which  certainly  assures  its  long  usefulness.  There 
are,  too,  many  paragraphs  of  appraisement  and  summary  which 
make  the  structure  of  the  thought  and  the  opinions  of  the  author 
at  once  evident,  frank  even  in  their  perfectly  legitimate  bias. 

Virtually  the  volume  before  us  is  a  monograph  on  Francis 
Bacon,  giving  first  an  account  of  his  life  and  the  motives  actuating 
the  composition  of  his  works;  second,  an  exposition  of  the  Bacon- 
ian classification  of  knowledge,  which  is  rightly  stressed  as  the  very 
heart  of  Bacon's  contribution;  and  lastly,  a  critical  examination 
of  the  philosophy  and  influence  of  the  great  empiricist.  Full  bibliog- 
raphy, index,  and  analytic  and  synthetic  tables  of  contents  make 
the  book  a  most  workable  reference. 

Of  the  general  aim  of  the  work  of  Father  Sortais  not  too  much 
can  be  said  in  praise.  Few  students  of  the  history  of  thought  at 
this  hour  will  doubt  that  the  European  development  has  reached 
one  of  the  nodes  of  its  changing  course  and  that  in  a  distinct  and 
dramatic  sense  a  period  has  come  to  its  close.  It  is  time  that  we 
should  set  about  writing  the  story  of  this  period — for  it  has  never 
yet  been  done,  and  in  particular  not  for  the  nations  and  years  in 
which  it  received  its  essential  color,  that  is,  England  and  France 
in  the  sixteenth-seventeenth  centuries.  The  author  is  beginning 
his  work  in  the  just  locus,  in  time  and  space,  and  is  treating  his 
affair  with  an  expansiveness  proportionate  to  its  importance.  On 
the  other  hand,  not  he  himself  pretends  that  what  he  is  giving  is 
more  than  a  study  in  materials.  He  justly  observes  that  the  per- 
spective must  grow  out  of  the  slow  analysis  of  the  works  of  men  in 
relation  to  their  times,  and  his  volumes  will,  in  a  sense,  be  propae- 
deutic to  the  vivid  characterization  of  the  thought  of  the  Northern 
Renaissance  (for  Bacon  to  Bergson  comprise  this)  which  some  future 
day  will  give. 

Meantime  for  the  picture  of  Bacon  himself  we  may  be  thoroughly 
appreciative.  The  influence  of  his  classification  of  knowledge  has 
been  very  much  greater  than  books  have  recognized,  affecting  the 
whole  encyclopaedic  and  educational,  and  hence  investigative  pro- 
gramme of  modern  times:  our  reference  books,  catalogues  and  cur- 


139 

ricula  are  all  essentially  Baconian,  and  it  may  well  be  doubted  if 
the  influence  of  the  philosopher  in  this  field  of  organization  is  not 
truly  speaking  of  far  greater  significance  than  his  popularization 
of  the  inductive  method.  We  say  "popularization"  with  intent, 
for  it  is  far  less  to  Francis  than  to  Roger  Bacon  that  its  emphatic 
discovery  is  due.  Indeed,  it  is  the  most  striking  weakness  of  Father 
Sortais 's  book  that  he  suggests  no  relationship  of  the  thought  of 
the  two  great  Englishmen.  The  recent  readings  of  the  cipher 
manuscript  of  Roger  Bacon  by  Professor  Newbold  are  throwing  an 
amazing  light  upon  the  discoveries  of  the  latter.  Further  studies 
of  the  history  of  the  manuscripts  of  Friar  Bacon  bid  fair  to  estab- 
lish beyond  cavil  the  continuity  of  the  Roger  Bacon  tradition  down 
to  Elizabethan  times  and  in  the  very  circles  in  which  Francis  Bacon 
moved.  It  may,  indeed,  turn  out  that  the  Jacobean  chancellor  of 
the  seventeenth  is  but  the  perpetuated  tongue — like  the  traditional 
head  of  speaking  bronze — of  the  half -heretical  Oxford  prisoner  of 
the  thirteenth  century.  Of  all  this  Father  Sortais  appears  to  know 
not  even  what  should  have  been  guessed  apart  from  the  manuscript 
discoveries,  and  the  lack  is  likely  to  sail  for  a  rewriting  of  his  chap- 
ters at  some  not  distant  date.  And  a  knowledge  of  the  strange 
twinship  of  the  two  Bacons  may  go  far  yet  to  explain  that  curious 
duality  of  Francis  Bacon's  character  which  Father  Sortais  (apolo- 
gist for  the  chancellor  as  he  often  is),  along  with  others,  finds 
therein.  For  we  can  not  quarrel  with  his  final  picture:  "The 
physiognomy  of  Bacon,  author  of  the  Novum  Organum  and  chancel- 
lor of  England,  unconquerably  evokes  the  antique  image  of  Janus 
bifrons.  Hence,  even  with  all  indulgence,  History,  that  it  may 
remain  impartial,  can  only  with  reservation  bestow  upon  him  the 
eulogy  of  greatness,  for  moral  grandeur,  which  naught  else  may 
supply,  was  wanting  in  him." 

H.  B.  ALEXANDER. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  NEBRASKA. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

SCIENTIA.  July,  1921.  National  Contributions  to  Geology 
(pp.  1-12)  :  J.  W.  GREGORY  (Glasgow). -Rapid  survey  of  the  history 
of  geology,  bringing  out  its  cosmopolitan  character.  La  constitution 
de  I'individualite.  II.  L'individualite  psychique  (pp.  13-24)  : 
AUGUSTO  Pi  SUNER  (Barcelona)  .-A  recommendation  of  behaviorist 
psychology.  Les  idees  nouvelles  sur  la  suggestion  (pp.  25-32) :  C. 
BAUDOUIN  (Geneva) .-Suggestion,  fallen  into  disrepute,  has  again 
been  rehabilitated  by  M.  fimile  Cone  and  his  disciples,  forming  the 


140  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

new  school  of  Nancy  in  psychiatry.  According  to  them  all  suggestion 
is  auto-suggestion  and  not  subjection  to  another.  It  works  subcon- 
sciously but  not  automatically.  A  suggestion  can  not  be  suppressed 
except  through  replacing  it  positively  by  another.  Conscious  fight- 
ing against  it  often  accelerates  it.  So  suggestion  must  be  distin- 
guished from  will,  which  proceeds  by  effort.  In  a  way,  this  theory 
is  a  scientific  application  of  what  is  vaguely  known  under  the  name 
of  the  influence  of  "morale."  Problemes  financiers  d'apres  guerre. 
II.  Pretevements  sur  le  capital  (pp.  33-54) :  CORBADO  GINI 
(Padua). -A  discussion  of  confiscatory  taxation,  especially  of  the 
disadvantages  of  a  tax  on  capital.  Reviews  of  Scientific  Books  and 
Periodicals. 

Diderot.  Entretien  entre  d'Alembert  et  Diderot,  Reve  d'Alembert, 
Suite  de  1'Entretien.  Collection  des  Chef s-d 'CEuvre  Meconnus, 
with  an  introduction  and  notes  by  Gilbert  Maire.  Paris:  Edi- 
tions Bossard.  1921.  Pp.  193.  12fr. 

Goblot,  Edmond.  Le  Systeme  des  Sciences:  Le  Vrai,  1'Intelligible, 
et  le  R4el.  Paris:  Armand  Colin.  1922.  Pp.  259.  7  fr. 

Guttler,  C.  Einfiihrung  in  die  Geschichte  der  Neueren  Philosophic 
des  Auslandes.  Miinchen:  Ernst  Reinhardt.  1922.  Pp.  221. 
15  in. 

Pound,  Roscoe.  The  Spirit  of  the  Common  Law.  Boston :  Marshal 
Jones  Co.  1921.  Pp.  xiv  +  224.  $2.50. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

We  have  just  learned  of  the  death  of  Mr.  L.  E.  Hicks  of  Berke- 
ley, Calif.,  in  November  1921.  Mr.  Hicks  contributed  a  number  of 
articles  on  logic  to  the  JOURNAL  during  the  last  few  years. 

Professor  Ralph  Barton  Perry  has  recently  begun  his  tour  of 
lectures  at  the  provincial  universities  of  France  for  the  Hyde 
Foundation. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  6.  MARCH  1G,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


DEMOCRACY  AND  MORALS 

IN  an  article  by  Cohen  that  appeared  in  the  New  Republic,  March 
17,  1920,  and  in  the  article  by  Sheldon  in  this  JOURNAL,  June 
6,  1921,  certain  misrepresentations  of  Dewey's  conception  of  de- 
mocracy are  so  persistently  ascribed  to  Dewey  as  to  raise  the  question 
whether  Cohen,  Sheldon  and  others  are  really  criticizing  the  thing 
to  which  alone  Dewey  applies  that  term,  namely,  moral  democracy. 
Since  the  Revolution  it  has  been  popularly  assumed — i.e.,  by  those 
who  do  not  reflect  critically — that  democracy  means  liberty,  in  the 
sense  of  the  absence  of  law  and  social  control;  fraternity,  in  the 
sense  of  the  absence  of  ranks  and  titles;  and  equality  in  the  sense 
of  equal  control  exercised  by  all  alike  over  the  material  and  spirit- 
ual resources  of  society.  The  readers  of  this  JOURNAL  surely  do  not 
require  proof  that  these  "ideals,"  taken  separately,  are  unnatural 
and,  taken  together,  are  mutually  incompatible.  Liberty,  so  con- 
ceived, is  incompatible  with  equality  as  denned ;  and  since  men  differ 
by  nature  in  taste  and  capacity,  fraternity  as  conceived  by  the  revo- 
lutionists can  never  be  anything  but  an  affectation.  The  rank  of  a 
man  is  indeed  but  the  guinea's  stamp,  and  the  man's  the  gold;  but 
the  immortal  Burns  knew  better  than  most  that  men  differ  in  metal 
and  that  merely  stamping  them  does  not  always  make  guineas. 

It  is  difficult  for  any  student  of  life  to  enter  sympathetically 
and  intelligently  into  the  viewpoint  and  method  of  another,  but 
progress  in  the  discussion  of  philosophical  problems  depends  upon 
our  making  the  effort.  The  signers  of  this  paper  accordingly  venture 
to  say  that  the  key  to  Dewey's  use  of  the  term  democracy  is  liberty, 
rather  than  equality,  but  not  the  liberty  of  the  revolutionists,  not 
liberty  in  the  merely  negative  sense  of  the  absence  of  restraint  and 
control.  Liberty  means  the  absence  of  arbitrary  restraint,  of  un- 
just control :  liberty  is  opportunity  to  do  right :  but  the  moral  mean- 
ing of  the  word  is,  simply,  opportunity  for  each  and  all  to  beat  their 
music  out,  to  live  the  best  life  they  are  capable  of,  to  make  the  best 
contribution  to  the  material  and  spiritual  resources  of  society  they 
can.  When  one  considers  what  an  unformed  mass  of  possibilities 
each  child  is  as  it  comes  into  the  world,  the  applications  of  this 
realistic  conception  of  liberty  are  many  and  clear.  All  the  activities 
of  science,  for  example,  and  all  the  social  institutions  that  stimulate 

141 


142  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

and  encourage  them,  are  im-hulrd  in  this  conception  of  moral  de- 
mocracy. In  the  words  of  President  Lowell,  "Is  it  or  is  it  not 
desirable  that  men  in  the  community  should  yield  as  much  intellect- 
ual output  as  possible?  If  it  is,  how  is  it  undemocratic  in  men  any 
more  than  in  cowsT  Do  not  let  us  be  deceived.  Let  us  remember 
that  after  all  the  greatest  asset  of  a  community  is  not  its  mines,  or 
its  soil,  but  its  men ;  and  that  it  is  for  the  interest  of  the  whole  com- 
munity that  every  man  should  be  developed  to  the  utmost  point  to 
which  he  can  be  developed."  By  moral  democracy,  Dewey  means  a 
community  in  which  each  member  finds  heroic  stimulation  and  en- 
couragement to  be  and  do  his  best.  "The  end,  the  right  and  only 
right  end,  of  man,  lies  in  the  fullest  and  freest  realization  of  powers 
in  their  appropriate  objects.  The  good  consists  of  friendship,  family 
and  political  relations,  economic  utilization  of  mechanical  resources, 
science,  art,  in  all  their  complex  and  variegated  forms  and  elements. 
There  is  no  separate  and  rival  moral  good ;  no  separate,  empty  and 
rival  'good  will'  "  (Dewey  in  Dewey  and  Tuft's  Ethics).  "Har- 
mony, reinforcement  and  expansion  are  the  signs  of  a  true  or  moral 
satisfaction.  What  is  the  good  which  while  good  in  direct  enjoyment 
also  brings  with  it  richer  and  fuller  lifet"  Richer  and  fuller  life 
includes  pure  science,  art,  worship  and  contemplation,  the  develop- 
ment and  enjoyment  of  wealth,  the  making  and  administration  of 
law,  and  other  enterprises.  This  is  a  circular  definition,  of  course ; 
for  this  philosophy  is  founded  in  the  notion  of  inherent  value,  namely 
in  the  notion  of  the  inherent  value  of  the  experience  of  value.  Con- 
templation is  accordingly  either  good,  bad  or  indifferent;  to  say  that 
this  philosophy  has  no  place  for  contemplation  is  a  misreading  of  it. 
All  political  activities  are  tested  by  this  question:  Do  they  tend  to 
stimulate  and  develop  the  capacities  of  individuals  in  ways  that  ren- 
der them  available  for  the  social  good? 

The  good,  according  to  this  philosopher,  consists  of  self-conserv- 
ing and  self-promoting  activity,  i.e.,  of  activity  that  in  its  results 
tends  to  reinforce  and  expand  itself;  and  the  similarity  of  this  con- 
ception to  a  possible  interpretation  of  the  Kantian  maxim  is  obvious. 
However,  this  abstract  formula  in  its  sweeping  generality  is  prac- 
tically useless:  it  gives  little  or  no  help  to  anyone  confronted  with 
an  actual  moral  issue.  This  consideration  leads  to  the  conclusion 
that  the  real  value  of  an  act  is  unique,  that  each  concrete  moral 
situation  has  its  own  good;  and  this  means  that  moral  values  are 
immediate  and  concrete,  not  abstract  and  conceptual.  It  does  not 
mean  that  the  good  is  idiosyncratic  or  fanciful.  The  good  of  each 
moral  situation  is  as  universal  as  an  oak  tree,  as  real  as  the  first 
president  of  the  United  States. 

In  a  moral  democracy,  conflicts  of  claim  occur  naturally  and  in- 


DEMOCRACY  AND  MORALS  143 

evitably,  and  where  they  occur  this  ideal  means  that  the  parties 
concerned  refer  their  claims  to  a  common  good  and  cooperate  in 
achieving  that.  That  Dewey  recognizes  the  function  of  government 
in  settling  such  conflicts  is  evident  in  page  after  page  of  his  ethical 
discussions.  Thus,  he  remarks  that  no  other  such  instrument  as  the 
courts  with  their  juries  was  ever  devised  for  mediating  social  order 
and  progress.  Again,  every  right,  civil  or  political,  carries  with  it 
a  corresponding  duty  and  the  only  fundamental  anarchy  is  the  lay- 
ing claim  to  rights  without  acknowledging  corresponding  duties. 
The  enforcement  of  duties  through  law  and  its  administration  is 
abundantly  provided  for  in  this  theory  of  society.  That  Dewey 
believes  the  acquisition  and  ownership  of  private  property  to  be  a 
moral  good,  no  student  of  his  ethics  can  question.  Like  most  modern 
writers  on  politics  he  regards  public  judgment  as  a  most  important 
sanction  of  law,  but  he  recognizes  the  usefulness  and  necessity  of 
force  intelligently  applied. 

In  the  light  of  these  teachings  of  Dewey,  so  familiar  that  apologies 
are  in  order  for  reciting  them,  what  is  to  be  said  of  Cohen's  state- 
ment that  Dewey  has  deliberately  chosen  between  the  gospel  of 
mastery  over  nature  and  mastery  over  self  and  rejected  the  latter? 
Cohen  states  that  according  to  Dewey  all  ideas  are  and  ought  to  be 
"instruments  for  reforming  the  world,"  that  Dewey  uses  the  word 
practical  to  mean  tending  to  reform  the  cosmic  scenery  of  human 
life.  According  to  Dewey,  however,  the  human  self  is  a  part  of 
nature;  a  human  community  is  as  much  a  natural  phenomenon  as 
a  community  of  beavers.  Dewey  holds  that  the  particular  part  of 
nature  that  today  most  needs  scientific  treatment  leading  to  "mas- 
tery" over  it  is  the  part  that  never  yet  has  received  such  treatment, 
namely,  the  human  community  and  especially  the  human  self.  He 
reiterates  exactly  the  opposite  of  the  doctrine  that  Cohen  ascribes 
to  him.  He  enforces  the  necessity  of  applying  the  organa  of  scienti- 
fic intelligence  to  human  nature  in  order  that  the  manifold  problems 
of  politics,  economics,  preventive  medicine,  international  society, 
etc.,  etc.,  can  be  solved  through  effective  self-direction.  It  is  to  the 
end  of  human  self-mastery  that  Dewey  teaches  "reconstruction  in 
philosophy."  The  Baconian  slogan,  Knowledge  is  Power,  as  inter- 
preted by  Dewey,  means  that  before  man  can  hope  to  master  the 
social  conditions  (the  "scenery"  of  Cohen)  of  human  life,  he  must 
take  the  pains  to  study  and  know  them  adequately.  As  the  present 
writers  understand  Reconstruction  in  Philosophy,  that  is  the  partic- 
ular reconstruction  the  author  of  this  book  is  talking  about. 

Cohen  and  Sheldon  insist  that  Dewey  teaches  a  gospel  of  equal 
development  for  all.  Sheldon  writes,  in  his  discussion  of  Dewey 's 
late  book:  "Equal  development  is  undesirable;  it  would  indeed  be 


144  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

fatal  to  progress.  It  would  render  society  as  monotonous  as  the 
desert;  it  would  do  away  with  the  beautiful  economy  of  the  division 
of  labor,  with  individuality,  with  unique  achievement.  The  social 
democratic  heaven  of  equal  development  would  reduce  personality 
to  nothingness" — as  if  all  this  had  any  bearing  on  Dewey's  philos- 
ophy! "We  do  not  wish  to  make  men  equal  through  and  through; 
we  do  not  wish  the  ordinary  man  to  be  capable  of  doing  the  work  of 
the  expert ;  equality  should  pertain  only  to  certain  elementary  neces- 
sities of  life"  (italics  added).  To  the  present  writers  this  social 
philosophy  contrasts  violently  with  that  of  Dewey  and  Lowell ;  but 
it  is  impossible  for  us  to  understand  how  anyone  can  ascribe  the 
dogma  of  equal  development  for  all  to  Dewey.  In  his  books  on  edu- 
cation he  warns  against  the  standardization  of  school  children.  The 
individual  for  Dewey  has  a  duty  to  develop  to  the  utmost  his  partic- 
ular bent;  but  since  it  is  good  to  grow  competitively,  handicaps 
should  be  removed.  Unless  distinction  is  competitively  gained,  both 
the  individual  and  the  community  suffer. 

Dewey  writes  that  "regard  for  the  happiness  of  others  means 
regard  for  those  conditions  and  objects  which  permit  others  freely 
to  exercise  their  own  powers  from  their  own  initiative,  reflection  and 
choice."  Perhaps  this  doctrine  is  what  Cohen  and  Sheldon  have  in 
mind  as  the  doctrine  of  equal  development  for  all.  In  Dewey's 
thought  the  socially  available  capacities  of  each  should  find  stimula- 
tion and  heroic  encouragement  in  the  ' '  conditions  and  objects ' '  that 
make  up  his  social  and  physical  environment,  and  he  has  in  mind  the 
brilliantly  endowed  just  as  much  as  the  slow  and  dull.  Those  who 
have  heard  Dewey  in  the  lecture  room  are  amazed  to  learn  that  he 
wishes  "the  best  endowed  to  put  off  their  progress  until  the  least 
endowed  have  come  up  to  their  level."  On  the  contrary,  he  has  both 
advocated  and  practised  special  individual  training  for  the  best 
endowed  as  well  as  special  training  for  the  mentally  retarded. 

The  misreading  of  Dewey  on  the  part  of  Cohen  and  Sheldon  is 
due  to  a  failure  to  understand  what  he  means  by  moral  democracy. 
What  he  teaches  is  not  equality  of  possessions  either  material  or 
spiritual,  but  equality  of  opportunity  for  each  to  make  the  best  con- 
tribution to  the  material  and  spiritual  life  of  mankind  that  he  is 
capable  of.  Uniqueness  of  personal  achievement  is  precisely  the 
thing  that  Dewey  does  believe  in,  teach,  and  practise.  That 
these  two  writers  should  ascribe  to  him  exactly  the  opposite  doctrine, 
that  they  should  say  he  teaches  a  levelling  process  in  possessions  both 
material  and  spiritual,  must  strike  every  thorough  reader  of  Dewey 
as  strange  indeed.  Democracy  in  Dewey's  conception  is  perfectly 
compatible  with  the  meteoric  achievement  of  a  Shakspeare  or  a  New- 
ton :  it  is  not  incompatible  with  the  mysticism  of  St.  Francis  or 


DEMOCRACY  AND  MORALS  145 

Luther :  it  is  not  incompatible  with  the  achievements  of  those  modern 
captains  of  industry  who  have  contributed  enormously  to  the  wealth 
of  society  or  with  their  enormous  rewards  for  doing  so.  The  de- 
mocracy he  teaches  is  fundamentally  ethical.  Democracy  in  the 
sense  of  equal  amounts  of  control  over  the  spiritual  and  material 
resources  of  society,  democracy  in  the  sense  of  mob-rule,  democracy 
as  a  levelling  process,  democracy  in  any  sense  that  is  a  menace  to 
spiritual  values  or  to  unique  personal  achievement,  is  foreign  to  his 
thought.  Dewey  is  trying  to  forge  an  instrument  that  can  be  used 
effectively  in  the  solution  of  personal  and  social  problems,  the  ob- 
jective being  a  community  in  which  each  man  shall  find  encourage- 
ment to  be  contentedly  and  effectively  himself. 

Sheldon  and  Cohen  both  find  fault  with  Dewey  for  not  stating 
just  what  conditions  and  circumstances  will  environ  us  in  that 
society,  for  not  stating  just  what  customs,  laws  and  institutions  are 
supremely  just,  beneficent  and  efficient.  If  anyone  only  knew! 
Surely  the  writers  of  these  articles  do  not  exact  omniscience  of  the 
ethicist!  Or  demand  that  he  teach  some  particular  economic  doc- 
trine !  Desires,  inventions  and  changing  circumstances  condition  in 
detail  the  organization  of  the  community  from  day  to  day:  the  con- 
flicts, competitions  and  triumphs  of  men  help  to  determine  it:  and 
intelligence  can  not  anticipate  these  in  detail.  "Democracy,"  says 
a  writer  in  the  Atlantic,  "  is  a  gamble  on  the  reasonableness  of  human 
nature,"  but  its  method  of  achieving  results  is,  within  limits  set  by 
the  concept  of  democracy  itself,  competitive.  If  human  beings  are 
essentially  moral  beings,  as  we  assume  they  are,  we  must  believe  that 
all  customs  and  institutions  ought  to  be  educative  in  their  effects  on 
human  lives,  that  wealth  and  property  ought  to  be  subordinated  to 
personality  in  our  scale  of  values,  and  that  every  man  who  can  ought 
to  use  his  intelligence  reverently  and  scientifically  to  forge  a  moral 
future  out  of  the  given  present.  To  this  end,  philosophy  can  reason- 
ably be  expected  to  furnish  an  adequate  methodology.  Democracy 
exists  only  where  communities  daily  conquer  it  anew,  and  it  is  part 
of  its  working  credo  that  the  world  evolves  through  that  effort. 

This  we  believe  to  be  part  of  Dewey 's  meaning,  and  we  find  it 
antagonistic  to  nothing  in  civilization  that  we  habitually  regard  as 
precious.  It  is  antagonistic  to  the  belief  that,  before  the  determina- 
tion of  individual  powers  and  individual  distinction  by  competitive 
behavior,  "some  men  are  born  horses  while  others  are  born  with 
saddles  to  ride  them. ' '  It  affirms  that  no  one  should  be  prostituted 
to  the  status  of  a  mere  tool  of  another 's  will ;  for  the  exhortation  of 
Kant  is  the  acme  of  good  sense,  "Treat  humanity,  whether  in  thyself 
or  another,  always  as  an  end,  never  as  a  means."  In  Reconstruc- 
tion in  Philosophy,  an  elementary  presentation,  Dewey  emphasizes — 


146  JOURNAL  OF  PHlLOSOPll  Y 

perhaps  he  overemphasizes,  if  measured  by  the  standard  of  a  com- 
plete and  symmetrical  system  of  philosophy — the  instrumental  theory 
of  knowledge ;  but  this  means  at  most  that  those  who  study  his  teach- 
ings will  do  well  to  read  his  logical  discussions  in  conjunction  with 
his  moral,  educational  and  political  philosophy.  Whether  he  would 
subscribe  to  the  statement,  we  do  not  know,  but  some  of  his  writings 
suggest  to  us  the  doctrine  that  the  inherent  values  to  which  concepts 
are  instrumental  are  ultimately  inter  al.  moral  values. 

It  is  not  so  much  Dewey 's  philosophy  as  the  facts  of  nature  that 
negate  the  idea  of  identical  development  for  all  and  the  idea  of  equal 
participation  in  control  over  social  resources.  These  facts  of  nature 
are  canvassed  by  Dewey  in  various  writings,  and  his  theory  squares 
with  them.  Pure  science,  art,  worship  and  play  are  from  his  stand- 
point normal  activities  of  human  beings,  human  functions  that  cer- 
tain customs  of  modern  life  tend  to  pervert  or  suppress.  We  hire 
priests  to  do  our  praying  for  us,  professional  singers  to  do  our  prais- 
ing, ball  teams  and  actors  to  do  our  playing,  and  scientists  to  do 
our  thinking;  meanwhile,  we  devote  ourselves  to  a  mad  scramble  for 
ability  to  buy  things,  or  for  a  maximum  of  economic  control,  and 
wonder  at  the  poverty  and  barrenness  of  all  our  lives.  Is  it  "danger- 
ous" to  call  attention  to  the  fact  that  the  spiritual  enterprise  of 
reconstructing  and  mastering  the  self  is  not  an  enterprise  entirely 
different  from  that  of  understanding  and  controlling  "the  cosmic 
scenery"  ?  Sheldon  sees  fit  to  warn  his  readers  because  Dewey  has 
been  studied  and  quoted  by  malcontents.  The  implications  of  the 
warning  are  obvious  to  all  who  cherish  the  wisdom  of  Amos  and 
Socrates,  and  a  solution  of  the  question  of  the  method  of  determining 
the  dangerous  or  safe  quality  of  moral  ideas  can  not  be  reached  in 
a  summary  fashion.  The  way  of  Dewey  is  to  appeal  to  the  process 
of  history  and  the  long-run  confirmation  of  ideas  by  consequences. 
In  his  social  philosophy  Sheldon  appears  to  favor  medieval  realism 
and  the  logic  of  formal  authority  and  the  Index. 

G.  A.  TAWNEY, 
E.  L.  TALBERT. 
THE  UNIVERSITY  or  CINCINNATI. 


DR.  A.  N.  WHITEHEAD'S  SCIENTIFIC  REALISM 

fcfc  A  N -ism,"  it  has  been  well  said,  "i%by  its  inmost  being  always 
-£j-  in  opposition,"  and  the  conditions  which  have  governed  the 
development  of  current  realism  have  undoubtedly  given  it,  for  good 
or  evil,  a  markedly  protestant  character;  but  the  question  whether 
the  defects  of  this  general  attitude  outweigh  its  merits  must  here  be 
dismissed  with  the  remark  that  not  the  least  hostile  influence  oppos- 


WHITEHEAD'S  SCIENTIFIC  REALISM  147 

ing  the  new  tendency  has  been  the  subjectivism  aspect — whether 
frankly  such  or  masked  as  "idealist" — of  contemporary  science.  It 
serves  no  purpose,  again,  to  discuss  the  reasons  for  this  state  of 
things;  the  fact  must  just  be  accepted.  But  this  suffices  to  give  to 
any  exception  from  the  general  rule  an  unusual  degree  of  impor- 
tance; when  therefore  a  mathematician  and  physicist  essays  "the 
basis  of  a  natural  philosophy  which  is  the  necessary  presupposition 
of  a  recognized  speculative  physics"1 — reorganized,  that  is,  in  ac- 
cordance with  recent  developments — when  he  approaches  his  subject 
as  an  out  and  out  realist,  preluding  his  theory  by  an  emphatic  protest 
against  subjectivism,  the  course  of  his  investigation  at  once  assumes 
the  highest  degree  of  interest. 

Mark  first  of  all  the  uncompromising  emphasis  of  Dr.  Whitehead's 
protest.  "There  is  now  reigning  in  philosophy  and  in  science  an 
apathetic  acquiescence  in  the  conclusion  that  no  coherent  account  can 
be  given  of  nature  as  disclosed  in  sense-awareness  without  dragging 
in  its  relations  to  mind.  The  result  has  been  disastrous  both  to  science 
and  to  philosophy."  2  Even  if  philosophy  is  less  apathetic  than  Dr. 
Whitehead  supposes,  still  this  is  sufficiently  provocative;  it  raises 
most  of  the  questions  at  issue  at  the  moment.  What,  e.g.,  is  nature  ? 
Nature,  for  Dr.  Whitehead,  is  what ' '  we  observe  in  perception  through 
the  senses;  something  which  is  not  thought  and  which  is  self-con- 
tained for  thought."  Nature  is  "independent  of  thought"  in  the 
sense  that  it  "can  be  thought  of  as  a  closed  system  whose  mutual 
relations  do  not  require  the  expression  of  the  fact  that  they  are 
thought  about"  (p.  3).  In  saying  this  Dr.  Whitehead  is  fully  aware 
that  his  position  is  not,  metaphysically,  final.  But  he  is  not  aiming 
at  "metaphysical  doctrine";  all  he  desires  is  so  to  delimit  the  con- 
tent of  Nature  that  that  content  can  be  investigated  and  systematized 
without  confusing  the  inquiry  by  any  references  to  mind,  which, 
whatever  else  it  is,  is  not,  primarily  at  least,  nature.  He  posits  no 
metaphysical  "disjunction  of  nature  and  mind"  (p.  4),  but  accepts 
their  intimate  relation  and  union;  he  merely  wishes  reflectively  to 
extend  the  unreflective  attitude  of  everyday  experience,  which  puts 
"things"  on  one  side  and  "mind"  on  the  other,  to  scientific  thought 
in  general.3 

Nor  can  it  be  objected  that  such  a  procedure,  when  it  does  not 
ignore  the  issues,  simply  begs  the  question.  Problems  remain  in 
plenty ;  how,  e.g.,  "factors"  become  differentiated  from  "fact"  on  the 
one  hand  and  from  "entities"  on  the  other  (p.  13)  ;  the  relation, 

1  The  Concept  of  Nature,  by  A.  N.  Whitehead,  p.  vii 

2  Ibid.,  p.  27. 

«  P.  29:  "  adopting  our  immediate  instinctive  attitude  towards  perceptual 
knowledge. ' ' 


148  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

again,  between  sense-awareness  and  thought  (p.  14) ;  the  relative 
logical  priority  of  fact  and  factors;  and  many  another.  The  point 
here  is  that  these  questions  must  be  assigned  their  proper  position ; 
their  discussion  must  not  be  constantly  introduced  into  the  investi- 
gation of  Nature,  as  an  "illegitimate  importation  into  the  philosophy 
of  natural  Science"  (p.  28) — as  in  short  one  of  those  metaphysical 
red  herrings  which  disport  themselves  in  the  ocean  of  thought. 
Certainly  epistemology  is  in  one  aspect  a  natural  science  on  precisely 
the  same  footing,  e.g.,  as  physiology;  but  1  think  that  Dr.  White- 
head's  treatment  fully  justifies  his  conclusions,  despite  any  phil- 
osophic comments  which  may  quite  justifiably  be  made  on  them ;  and 
it  is  then  the  realism  of  his  developed  position  which  appears  to  me 
as  important  as  it  is  unusual. 

It  is  not,  in  the  first  place,  a  noumenal  realism;  both  "real"  sub- 
stratum and  "phenomenal"  attributes  are  dispensed  with,  as  depend- 
ing on  "a  distinction  which  is  no  distinction  at  all"  (p.  16) ;  and  with 
these,  again,  "primary"  and  "secondary"  qualities4  (p.  27) ;  the 
philosophy  of  science  then  becomes  "the  philosophy  of  the  thing  per- 
ceived. Everything  perceived  is  in  nature.  We  may  not  pick  and 
choose.  The  red  glow  of  sunset  should  be  as  much  part  of  nature 
as  are  molecules  and  electric  waves.  It  is  for  natural  philosophy 
to  analyze  how  these  elements  of  nature  are  connected,  refusing  to 
countenance  any  theory  of  psychic  additions  to  the  object  known 
in  perception"  (pp.  28,  29).  There  are  not,  in  brief,  two  natures, 
one  "apprehended  in  awareness,"  and  the  other  "the  cause  of  aware- 
ness"; "there  is  but  one  nature,  the  nature  which  is  before  us  in 
perceptual  knowledge"  (p.  40) ;  and  this  "one  nature,"  finally,  ia 
itself  not  merely  apparent,  as  contrasted,  i.e.,  with  "conceptual 
formulae  of  calculation"  such  as  molecules  and  ether  (p.  45). 

Dr.  Whitehead's  adoption  of  such  a  definite  standpoint,  enforced 
by  the  arguments  set  forth  in  the  first  two  chapters  of  his  book, 
undoubtedly  constitutes  a  weighty  confirmation  of  the  main  conten- 
tions of  realism,  doubly  valuable  and  encouraging  as  coming  from 
an  independent  and  (primarily)  non-philosophic  quarter.  It  marks, 
it  is  to  be  hoped,  a  turning  point  in  the  course  of  discussion.  Science, 
hitherto  a  powerful,  even  if  passive,  ally  of  subjectivist  ontology, 
promises  to  transfer  her  support  and  allegiance  to  the  opposite 
camp.6  For  Dr.  Whitehead  is  by  no  means  alone  in  his  views, 
although  he  has  given  them  more  precise  and  systematic  form  than 

4  It  may  be  of  interest  to  point  out  that  before  Locke,  to  whom  Dr.  White- 
head  seems  to  assign  this  distinction,  it  had  been  endorsed  by  two  great  scien- 
tists— Boyle  and  Galileo. 

&  Dr.  Whitehead  'a  psychology,  as  very  briefly  outlined  on  p.  188,  seems  to  be, 
however,  unnecessarily  subjectivist.  I  can  not  help  thinking  that  his  whole  posi- 
tion would  be  improved  by  the  extension  of  realism  to  this  aspect  of  the  subject. 


WHITEHEAD'S  SCIENTIFIC  REALISM  149 

any  of  his  collaborators.  The  investigators  of  radio-activity  and  its 
developments  are  prepared  to  accord  to  electrons,  atoms,  and  mole- 
cules, with  their  mass  properties  and  spatial  configurations,  a  reality 
that  is  continuous  and  truly  consubstantial  with  that  of  the  macro- 
scopic objects  of  every-day  experience.6  Realism  of  this  type,  again, 
appears  to  me  to  accord  with  Platonic  and  Hegelian  idealism,  so 
long  as  it  does  not  explicitly  question  those  presuppositions  in  virtue 
of  which,  as  realism,  it  exists.  But  these  Dr.  Whitehead,  from  his 
scientific  standpoint,  is  entitled  to  ignore;  they  lie,  as  he  contends, 
outside  his  province,  and  to  force  them  into  prominence  only  con- 
fuses the  issue;  and  confining  myself  in  the  main  to  the  same  point 
of  view — "endeavoring  to  exhibit  the  type  of  relations  which  hold 
between  the  entities  we  perceive  as  in  nature"  (p.  45) — I  should 
like  to  consider  his  results.  It  is  peculiarly  difficult,  however,  for 
those  who  are  principally  interested  in  philosophy  to  appreciate 
the  precise  character  of  Dr.  "Whitehead 's  aim.  He  is  concerned  with 
the  known  content  of  Nature,  with  its  adequate  description  and 
analysis;  so  that  considerations  of  genesis,  whether  psychological  or 
epistemological,  as  also  of  logical  priority,  either  do  not  arise  at  all 
or  enter  into  the  discussion  only  indirectly  and  remotely ;  and  unless 
this  is  constantly  borne  in  mind  his  work  can  not  be  properly  appre- 
ciated. 

1.  There  appears  to  be  a  fundamental  difficulty  at  the  outset, 
in  the  explication  given  on  pp.  13-15.  ' '  There  are  three  components 
in  our  knowledge  of  nature,  fact,  factors,  and  entities.  Fact  is  the 
undifferentiated  terminus  of  sense-awareness;  factors  are  termini, 
differentiated  as  elements  of  fact."  Next,  "the  immediate  fact"— 
undifferentiated,  that  is — "is  the  whole  occurrence  of  nature  as  an 
event  present  for  sense-awareness,  and  essentially  passing.  The  ulti- 
mate fact  (undifferentiated),  for  sense-awareness  is  an  event.  This 
whole  event  is  discriminated  into  partial  events. ' '  Thus,  beginning 
from  nature,  we  have  two  parallel  divisions  of  one  and  the  same 
total  content,  (a)  as  "fact"  into  "factors"  and  (&)  as  "event"  into 
"partial  events";  and  since  both  factors  and  events  derive  from  the 
same  original  totality — since  all  the  factors  make  up  the  fact  which 
is  again  the  whole  event  made  up  by  events — then  it  would  seem 
that  events  and  factors  must  be  somehow  equivalent  to  each  other; 
factors,  i.e.,  must  be  events,  and  events,  factors.  But  this  is  not  the 
case;  for  there  are  "other  factors  in  nature  which  are  not  events."  7 
But  if  this  is  true,  then  it  would  seem  to  follow  either  (a)  that  the 
whole  of  events  is  not  really  a  whole,  because  it  omits  some  factors ; 

«  Cf.  Nature,  Nov.  6,  1919,  p.  230. 

7  Cf.  p.  124 — ' '  other  factors  of  nature  which  do  not  share  in  the  passage  of 
events. ' ' 


150  JOURNAL  OF  PHlLOSOPlt  Y 

or  (6)  the  whole  is  not  an  event,  because  it  contains  factors  which 
are  not  events.  Both  alternatives  materially  affect  Dr.  Whitehead's 
theory  of  time  and  space,  because  these  are  "abstractions  from 
events."8 

The  obscurity  on  this  point  is  increased  when  these  factors 
Avhii'h  are  not  events  become  later  on  defined  as  "objects";  for 
some  objects  at  least  are  only  intellectual  abstractions.  "Objects 
for  our  knowledge  may  be  merely  logical  abstractions  .  .  .  the 
object  ...  is  a  mere  abstract  concept  ...  an  abstract  relation, 
although  it  is  there  in  nature"  (p.  126).  Obviously  we  have 
travelled  a  long  way  from  sense-awareness  and  its  content;  and  I 
recur  to  the  subject  later  on  in  connection  with  "moments." 

A  somewhat  similar  ambiguity  marks  the  more  special  treat- 
ment of  time  in  Chap.  III.  Again  we  find  (p.  49),  "in  the  first 
place  there  is  posited  a  general  fact ;  something  is  going  on ;  there 
is  an  occurrence  for  definition."  At  first  sight  this  seems  to  ac- 
cord with  the  preceding  statement  already  considered;  we  have  a 
totality  which  is  an  event,  and  which  may  be  further  distinguished 
either  into  events  or  into  factors;  but  the  fact  which  was  previ- 
ously defined  as  the  undifferentiated  terminus  of  sense-awareness, 
here  comprises  two  "sets  of  entities,  entities  perceived  in  their  own 
individuality  and  other  entities  apprehended  as  relata."  The 
first  are  then  "discerned,"  and  constitute  "the  field  directly  per- 
ceived"; the  others  are  "discernible"  and  are  in  relation  to  the 
discerned — directly  perceived — field;  and  "this  complete  general 
fact  is  the  discernible  and  comprises  the  discerned."  How  then 
can  "fact,"  or  "complete  general  fact,"  be  undifferentiated T 
There  are  two  alternatives :  (a)  it  falls  apart  into  the  two  mutually 
exclusive  divisions  of  discernible  and  discerned;  or  (&)  it  is  dis- 
cernible and  includes  (comprises)  the  discerned,  but  if  so,  it  can 
only  be  discernible  relatively  to  something  discerned.  Both  alter- 
natives therefore  imply  differentiation.  "Fact,"  i.e.,  has  lost  its 
primary  undifferentiated  character,  as  is  further  shown  by  its  con- 
stituents now  being  "relata  in  definite  relations  to  some  definite 
entities  in  the  discerned  field."  Thus  the  primitive  absence  of 
differentiation  has  given  place  to  definiteness  of  relation.9 

2.  But  let  us  accept  this  distinction  between  discernible  and 

•  Cf.  p.  13 — ' '  in  the  course  of  analysis  space  and  time  should  appear. "    It  is 
important  to  notice  Dr.  Whitohcad  's  attitude  on  this  point  as  compared  with  Pro- 
fessor Alexander 's  theory  of  space  and  time.    For  him  ' '  Space-Time  is  the  stuff 
out  of  which  all  existente  are  made.    Existents  are  complexes  of  Space-Time  " 
(Proc.  Ariel.  8oc.,  Vol.  XVII,  p.  417,  and  Space,  Time  and  Deity).     For  Dr. 
Whitehead,  ou  the  other  hand,  ' '  space  and  time  spring  from  a  common  root,  and 
the  ultimate  fact  of  experience  is  a  space-time  fact  "  (p.  132). 

•  "  Discernible  "  again  has  two  senses:  a  wider  on  p.  50  ("  complete  gen- 
eral fact  "),  and  a  narrower  on  p.  53  ("  general  present  fact  "). 


WHITEHEAD'S  SCIENTIFIC  REALISM  151 

discerned.  The  next  important  point  is  Dr.  Whitehead's  exposi- 
tion of  the  connection  between  Nature  and  sense-awareness.  He 
has  carefully  worked  out  the  relations  between  sense-awareness, 
mind  and  thought ;  and  if  it  were  possible  to  do  so  I  should  refrain 
from  any  further  discussion;  the  subject  pertains,  as  Dr.  White- 
head  contends,  to  mind  rather  than  to  Nature. 

But  his  position  here  has  so  important  a  bearing  on  his  philoso- 
phy of  Nature  that  some  comment  is  unavoidable.  He  seems  to  me 
to  have  followed  that  perilous  tendency  which  (as  a  reaction 
against  subjective  idealism)  attends  all  realism — that  is  to  attach 
undue  importance  to  sense-awareness,  as  such.  He  tends  to  hypo- 
statize  sense-awareness,  to  isolate  it  overmuch  from  mind  operat- 
ing as  a  whole,  somewhat  as  faculty  psychology  distinguished  be- 
tween will  and  thought  and  feeling.  Consider,  e.g.,  the  assertion 
(p.  14)  "the  immediate  fact  for  awareness  is  the  whole  occurrence 
of  nature. ' ' 10  Obviously  this  can  not  be  taken  literally ;  no  one 
can  be  sensibly  aware  of,  or  even  perceive,  the  whole  of  Nature. 
Given  the  conditions,  Nature  may  be  discernible  or  perceivable  or 
' '  awarable " ;  "  and  then  molecules,  electrons  and  electric  waves 
are  "parts  of  nature"  (p.  29).  They  would  appear  therefore  to 
be  "natural  entities";  but  on  the  other  hand  "entities  are  factors," 
and  "factors  are  termini  of  sense-awareness,"  which  "discloses 
factors  which  are  the  entities  for  thought";  further,  the  relations, 
"between  natural  entities  are  themselves  natural  entities — factors — 
there  for  sense-awareness"  (pp.  12-14).  This  is  sufficiently  defi- 
nite ; 12  but  plainly  in  two  directions — with  regard  to  Nature  in 
its  entirety  as  in  its  minutest  constituents — the  two  terms,  sense- 
awareness  and  perception,  bear  the  widest  possible  meaning ;  for  in 
both  aspects  Nature  actually  becomes  known  through  sense-aware- 
ness supplemented  by  conception,  inference  and  calculation;  but 
in  both  aspects,  again,  Nature  is  real;  for  "scientific  laws  are 
statements  about  entities  in  nature:  molecules  and  electrons  are 
factors  in  nature"  (pp.  45,  46). 

But  when  Dr.  Whitehead  undertakes  a  more  systematic  analy- 
sis of  Nature,  results  vitally  different  are  obtained  as  to  the  "enti- 
ties posited  for  knowledge  in  sense-awareness."  In  Chap.  III.  we 
find  that  what  may  be  called  the  unit  factor  or  initial  datum  of 
these  natural  entities  is  a  complex  "event — a  place  through  a 

10  Cf.  also,  "  the  philosophy  of  science  is  the  philoeophy  of  the  thing  per- 
ceived.   Everything  perceived  is  in  nature.     Nature  is  that  which  we  observe  in 
perception  through  the  senses  "  (pp.  28,  29,  30). 

11  Cf.  p.  52,  ' '  signified  events  include  events  in  the  past  as  well  as  the 
future  " ;  an  event  being  ' '  a  place  through  a  period  of  time. ' ' 

12  Ibid.,  "  the  complete  general  fact  which  is  all  nature  now  present  as  dis- 
closed in  sense-awareness. ' ' 


152  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

period  of  time"  —  a  complex,  i.e.,  within  which  space,  time,  and 
other  entities  may  be  discriminated.  The  totality  of  simultaneous 
events  constitutes  another  fundamental  datum,  a  "duration,  a  com- 
plex of  partial  events";  and  both  events  and  durations  possess,  es- 
-••ntially,  "temporal  thickness"  —  "a  duration  is  a  concrete  slab  of 
nature,  an  essential  factor  disclosed  in  sense-awareness;  not  a  mere 
abstract  stretch  of  time."  It  is,  in  short,  a  longer  or  briefer  proc- 
ess of  nature  just  as  it  happens  in  time  —  filling  up  time  as  it  were. 

Contrasted  with  this  is  the  "moment,"  as  the  content  of  "all 
nature  at  an  instant,"  with  "no  temporal  extension"  or  thickness; 
and  then  it  is  essential  to  the  whole  of  Dr.  Whitehead's  developed 
theory  that  while  durations  (including  events),  being  "directly 
yielded  to  knowledge  by  sense-awareness,  '  '  are  definite  natural  enti- 
ties and  "have  all  the  reality  that  nature  has,"  the  moment  on  the 
other  hand  "is  not  itself  a  natural  event;  in  truth  there  is  no  na- 
ture at  an  instant";  it  is  a  nonentity;  Dr.  Whitehead,  in  short, 
adopts  what  may  be  called  a  quantum  theory  of  temporal  nature.1' 

Xow  on  what  is  this  fundamental  contrast  founded?  It  is 
based,  consistently  with  Dr.  Whitehead's  acceptance  of  sense-aware- 
ness as  the  criterion  of  natural  content,  on  the  evidence  afforded 
by  that  type  of  consciousness.  "There  is  no  such  thing  as  nature 
at  an  instant  posited  by  sense-awareness.  What  sense-awareness 
delivers  over  for  knowledge  is  nature  through  a  period.  Accord- 
ingly nature  at  an  instant  is  not  itself  a  real  entity";  it  is  at  best 
"a  very  useful  concept." 

This  course  of  argument  seems  to  raise  two  serious  difficulties. 
In  the  first  place,  even  if  we  accept  the  content  of  sense-awareness 
as  our  criterion,  the  question  of  the  real  existence  of  moments  is 
determined  by  precisely  the  same  method  as  is  that  of  the  real  ex- 
istence of  electrons  and  molecules;  that  is,  by  a  process  of  infer- 
ence or  reasoning.14  This  process,  no  doubt,  must  begin  from  the 
real  data  of  sense-awareness;  but  it  is  impossible  to  maintain,  in 
either  case,  that  the  truth  of  the  conclusion  can  be  determined  by 
sense-awareness  as  such,  no  matter  how  wide  a  meaning  be  given 
to  this  term.  But  Dr.  Whitehead  regards  molecules  and  electrons 
as  real  existent  factors  in  nature  ;  moments,  on  the  other  hand,  are 
not  natural  entities.  And  his  ground  for  this  denial  of  reality  is  not 
that  it  is  irrational  or  inconceivable,  but  simply  that  it  is  not  a 
deliverance  of  sense-awareness  —  "there  is  no  such  thing  posited  by 
But  exactly  the  same  may  be  said  of  electrons 


"It  may  elucidate  Dr.  Whitehead's  position  to  refer  to  Lotze's  distinction 
between  empty  time  as  "  a  creation  of  our  intellect  '  '  and  '  '  the  succession  belong- 
ing to  (the  operation  of  things)  itself,  which  is  the  most  proper  nature  of  the 
real.  '  '  Metaphytic,  I,  pp.  350,  354. 

"  The  exact  logical  character  of  this  process  is  here  immaterial. 


WHITEHEAD'S  SCIENTIFIC  REALISM  153 

and  molecules.  Sense-awareness  combined  with  one  course  of  reason- 
ing gives  us  the  idea  of  moments;  these  Dr.  Whitehead  regards  as 
unreal,  ultimately  because  sense-awareness,  delivering  nature 
through  a  period,  does  not  posit  them.  Sense-awareness  again,  com- 
bined with  another  course  of  reasoning  similar  in  character  though 
differing  in  details,  yields  the  idea  of  electrons;  but  these  are  real, 
although  sense-awareness  (purely  as  such)  plainly  does  not  posit 
these  either.  Thus  the  merely  negative  verdict  of  awareness  is  en- 
dorsed in  one  case,  but  repudiated  in  the  other. 

But  as  I  have  already  pointed  out,  Dr.  Whitehead  admits  the 
existence  of  natural  factors — "there  in  nature" — which  though 
"not  posited  by  sense-awareness  may  be  known  to  the  intellect — 
not  disclosed  in  sense-awareness  but  known  by  logical  inference  as 
necessarily  in  being"  (pp.  125,  126).  These  entities  may  be  of 
fundamental  importance;  e.g.,  "identity  of  quality  between  con- 
gruent segments  is  generally  of  this  character";  and  the  theory  of 
congruence  occupies  the  whole  of  Chap.  VI.  Thus  Dr.  Whitehead 
accepts  the  general  principle  that  logical  inference  may  contribute 
to  the  determination  of  the  content  of  nature;  so  that  it  appears 
quite  illegitimate  to  rule  out  the  existence  of  moments  simply  on 
the  ground  that  they  are  not  posited  in  sense-awareness. 

I  am  not  of  course  arguing  that  moments  have  real  existence, 
nor  am  I  resorting  to  any  metaphysical  theory  to  decide  the  ques- 
tion; I  merely  suggest  that  Dr.  Whitehead 's  arguments,  as  they 
stand,  are  insufficient  to  establish  the  nonentity  of  moments.  And 
this  leads  to  the  second  difficulty  attending  his  position;  for  it  is 
by  no  means  so  certain  as  he  assumes  it  to  be  that  sense-awareness 
does  actually  posit  events  or  durations  having  temporal  thickness 
or  persistence.  Again  I  do  not  deny  the  existence,  within  the  con- 
tent of  sense-awareness,  of  durations  in  Dr.  Whitehead 's  special 
sense;  but  there  are  weighty  considerations  which  he  has  ignored 
which  make  it  impossible  to  accept  this  durational  character  as  per- 
taining to  nature  itself  merely  on  the  evidence  of  sense-awareness. 
For  it  is  possible  that  the  durational  aspect  of  this  content  is 
partially  or  even  completely  deceptive,  and  arises  from  the  condi- 
tions determining  consciousness;  conditions  which  are  of  course  in 
no  sense  metaphysical  but  purely  natural,  as  Dr.  Whitehead  him- 
self points  out  on  p.  107.  I  do  not  assert  that  this  durational 
character  is  deceptive,  but  only  that  this  possibility  is  not  absolutely 
excluded  by  Dr.  Whitehead 's  theory;  so  that  duration  may  be  an 
added  quality  conferred  by  sense-awareness  itself15  upon  its  con- 
tent even  while  that  content  is  at  the  same  time  a  natural  reality 
(or  a  nature)  wholly  non-durational.  It  is  true  that  Dr.  White- 
is  Not,  be  it  noted,  by  any  other  (ideal  or  conceptual)  type  of  consciousness. 


154  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

head  refuses,  on  what  are,  I  think,  good  grounds,  "to  countenance 
any  theory  of  psychic  additions  to  the  object  known  in  perception" 
(p.  29).  But  this  does  not  exclude  the  possibility — I  suggest 
nothing  more — of  awareness  or  observation  conferring  its  own  dura- 
tional  character18  upon  a  durationless  nature:  and  the  same  ap- 
plies to  the  remarks  on  p.  187.  That  the  duration  does  not  wholly 
pertain  to  Nature  is  a  fact  of  elementary  psychology;  but  it  is 
further  by  no  means  inconceivable  that  a  completely  non-dura- 
tional  nature  may  give  rise  by  perseveration  and  after-imagery 
within  sense-awareness  to  a  durational  content.  Were  we  to  assume 
indeed  that  electrons  were  perceivable,  then  their  enormous  veloci- 
ties and  infinitesimal  dimensions  would  result  in  something  closely 
approaching  if  not  identical  with  this  state  of  things.17 

These  considerations  in  no  way  alter  the  problem  of  natural  phi- 
losophy. That  is  still,  in  Dr.  Whitehead's  words,  "to  discuss  the 
relations  inter  se  of  things  known  abstracted  from  the  bare  fact  that 
they  are  known"  (p.  30).  But  knowledge  must  not  be  wholly  iden- 
tified with  sense-awareness;  rather  must  the  latter  be  criticized  in 
the  light  of  fuller  knowledge  in  order  to  ascertain  what  distinctions, 
if  any,  obtain  between  its  special  content  and  Nature  itself.  Dr. 
Whitehead,  however,  prevents  this  being  done  by  anticipation;  for 
the  two  conditions  which  he  assumes18  for  durations  preclude  in 
advance  any  possibility  of  the  reality  of  moments.  "Nature,"  in 
short,  "is  nothing  else  than  the  deliverance  of  sense-awareness" 
(p.  185). 

And  fundamentally  difficult  though  it  undoubtedly  is  to  regard 
an  event  as  a  sequence  or  sum  or  group  of  instantaneous  moments, 
still  Dr.  Whitehead's  later  theory  of  "objects"  seems  to  leave  us  no 
other  alternative.  An  event,  as  we  have  seen,  has  (essentially)  "tem- 
poral thickness";  and  it  also  (as  a  whole)  "passes."  Still  this  in 
itself  does  not,  I  think,  prevent  us  from  thinking  of  an  event  as  con- 
taining within  itself  constituents  which,  although  they  possess  the 
slightest  possible  temporal  thickness,  and  are  therefore  not  instan- 
taneous, still  do  not  themselves  ' '  pass. ' '  There  does  not  seem  to  me 
to  be  anything  illogical  about  this  possibility;  Dr.  Whitehead,  how- 
ever, excludes  it  by  definition.  For  any  element  in  nature  which 
does  not  pass  is-  an  object;  and  an  object  is  not  an  event;  the  char- 
acteristics of  the  two  are  mutually  exclusive,  in  spite  of  their  insep- 

i«  In  fact  Dr.  Whitehead  points  out  the  ' '  passage  of  sense-awareness  and  of 
thought  ";  i.e.  of  sense-awareness  as  an  activity — "  a  procedure  of  mind  " — 
not  as  a  content  or  terminus.  But  here  again  his  distinction  between  passage 
and  duration  seems  quite  arbitrary,  or  even  to  have  a  metaphysical  basis!  (Pp. 
66-73.) 

i*  Cf.  the  express  train  illustration,  p.  109. 

«  P.  60 ;  that  it  is  an  assumption  is  obvious. 


WHITEHEAD'S  SCIENTIFIC  REALISM  155 

arable  inter-connection  (pp.  143,  144,  169).  Now  blue  is  one  object; 
a  coat  is  another  and  an  electron  is  a  third ;  and  I  think  it  is  unde- 
niable that  all  these  have  temporal  thickness;  by  which  (with  Dr. 
Whitehead)  I  do  not  mean  "a  particular  second  at  a  definite  date" 
(p.  149)  but  rather  the  temporal  raw  material  given  in  awareness 
out  of  which  dates  and  seconds  are  obtained,  it  matters  not  how. 
Thus  objects,  as  such,  have  temporal  thickness.19  Any  constituent 
of  an  event  therefore  which  has  any  temporal  thickness,  no  matter 
how  slight,  and  which  does  not  pass,  is  not  an  event,  but  an  object ; 
so  that  the  only  possible  ultimate  events'  proper  must  be  instantane- 
ous. As  I  have  said  already,  Dr.  Whitehead  seems  to  me  to  avoid 
this  conclusion  only  by  the  prior  assumption  of  properties  of  dura- 
tion which  exclude  it  in  advance  (p.  60).  Still  we  may  in  a  certain 
sense  speak  of  "an  object  at  an  instant"  (p.  161)  ;  what  then  dis- 
tinguishes this  from  an  instantaneous  event?  Plainly  the  fact  that 
in  obtaining  temporal  thickness  it  does  not  pass;  or  in  other  words 
that  the  event,  to  be  an  event,  must  retain  its  passage  even  while  it 
assumes  temporal  thickness.  To  say  that  this  reduces  the  event- 
particle  or  the  moment  to  an  abstraction  is  no  valid  objection,  for 
' '  to  be  an  abstraction  .  .  .  means  that  its  existence  is  only  one  factor 
of  a  more  concrete  element  of  nature"  (p.  171). 

The  exact  meaning  of  the  passage  however  is  somewhat  uncertain. 
' '  Each  duration  happens  and  passes.  The  process  of  nature  can  also 
be  termed  the  passage  of  nature"  (p.  54).  This  seems  to  mean  that 
events  come  into  being  and  pass  away,  which  would  constitute  their 
uniqueness;  objects,  on  the  other  hand,  do  not  pass.  The  idea  cer- 
tainly appears  to  imply  activity;  and  on  p.  185  passage  is  given  as 
an  alternative  for  activity.  This  however  would  imply  that  objects 
are  never  active.  At  the  same  time  "the  event  is  what  it  is,  because 
the  object  is  what  it  is;  each  object  is  in  some  sense  ingredient 
throughout  nature.  The  ingression  of  every  electron  into  nature 
modifies  to  some  extent  the  character  of  every  event"  (pp.  144,  145, 
159).  It  is  obviously  difficult  therefore,  particularly  if  electrons 
are  eternal,  to  regard  objects  as  essentially  inactive;  so  that  this 
equivalence  between  passage  and  activity  is  not  easy  to  comprehend. 

4.  A  few  remarks  in  conclusion  on  the  distinctive  standpoints  of 
science  and  philosophy  with  regard  to  space  and  time  may  not  be 
superfluous.  Science  regards  these  entities  as  essentially  measured 
(or  at  least  measurable)  systems  which  together  constitute  the  space- 
time  manifold.  This  means  that  the  results  of  measurement  are  fully 
as  important  as  that  which  is  measured,  perhaps  more  important; 

i»  This  seems  to  be  supported  by  each  object  being  ingredient — i.e.,  active, 
operative,  influential — throughout  nature  (pp.  145,  159).  A  musical  tune,  again, 
is  also  an  object. 


156  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

in  other  words,  the  different  time-  and  space-systems  are  as  material 
to  thought  as  time  and  space  themselves.  Philosophy  however  takes 
a  somewhat  profounder  view ;  for  it  time  and  space  are  in  their  own 
nature  more  significant  than  the  scientific  systems;  somewhat  as  the 
monetary  system  of  his  own  country  is  of  primary  interest  to  a 
banker,  while  an  economist  is  more  concerned  with  currency  as  an 
element  in  universal  exchange.  And  now  that  the  space-time  mani- 
fold has  attained  such  prominence,  it  is  well  to  remember  that  it  is 
no  mysterious  entity  additional  to  time  and  space  themselves,  as 
though  it  were  something  wholly  different  in  its  nature  within  which 
these  disappear  or  dissolve.  Any  such  view  would  be  to  repeat  the 
error  so  often  made  in  dealing  with  time  and  space  by  erecting  them 
into  independent  realities.  The  manifold  is  but  the  coexistence  or 
unity  of  space  and  time,  which  coexist  within  reality  in  their  own 
characters,  like  nitrogen  and  oxygen  in  air,  not  compounded  into  a 
third  wholly  different  substance  like  oxygen  and  hydrogen  in  water. 
Regarded  in  this  light,  there  is  one  subject  of  essential  import- 
ance— the  uniformity  of  time  and  space  throughout  the  universe, 
as  distinct,  i.e.,  from  any  uniformity  of  time  and  space  systems.  As 
to  the  latter,  there  can  be  no  question;  observers  in  different  situa- 
tions must  employ  separate  though  interrelated  systems.  We  may 
some  day  obtain  both  a  common  language  and  a  general  currency; 
but  it  is  impossible  for  a  universal  time  and  space  system  ever  to 
be  constructed  and  employed ;  the  very  conditions  of  physical  reality 
forbid  it.  But  this  still  leaves  open  the  question  of  the  uniformity 
of  time  and  space;  the  latter,  e.g.,  has  been  described  as  bent  or 
warped  or  condensed  in  the  vicinity  of  matter.  Are  these  and  other 
similar  statements  metaphorical  or  literal  ?  Mathematical  devices  or 
descriptions  of  reality?  Dr.  Whitehead,  being  naturally  concerned 
with  systems,  leaves  the  subject  in  some  obscurity,  in  spite  of  his 
repudiation  of  Einstein's  own  interpretation  (p.  165).  "What  a 
being  under  the  one  set  of  circumstances  means  by  space  will  be 
different  from  that  meant  by  a  being  under  the  other  set"  (p.  168) ; 
so  that  English  and  Martian  observers  will  obtain  different  results 
from  any  one  Earth  land  survey.  But  what  is  it  that  thus  deter- 
mines local  differences  in  circumstances  f  In  the  end  all  circum- 
stances resolve  themselves  into  events.  ' '  The  concrete  facts  of  nature 
are  events;  event-particles  are  the  ultimate  elements  of  the  mani- 
fold" (pp.  167,  173).  Why,  then,  the  question  becomes,  are  events 
for  A  different  from  events  for  B  ?  *°  Martians  employ  space  natural 

20  Or  event- particles;  but  any  truly  final  explanation  must  be  in  terms  of  th« 
concrete  events.  It  is  assumed  of  course  that  A  and  B  both  have  minds  of  one 
and  the  same  general  type,  otherwise  the  basis  of  difference  is  not,  in  Dr.  White- 
head  'B  sense,  natural. 


THE  SIGNIFICANT  SYMBOL  157 

to  them — ' '  Martio-centric  space  in  which  that  planet  is  fixed.  Thus 
the  g-space  for  Mars  is  quite  different  from  the  p-space  on  earth" 
(pp.  175,  176).  This  however  must  not  be  taken  to  mean  that  the 
Martian  manifold  is  necessarily  different  from  ours,  for  space  and 
time  denote  only  the  relative  systems — "are  merely  ways  of  express- 
ing certain  truths  about  the  relations  between  events"  (p.  168).  If 
then  the  manifold  itself  is  uniform,  what  is  the  basis  of  the  unavoid- 
able differentiation  among  the  systems?  It  is  scarcely  sufficient  to 
fall  back  on  the  "creative  advance  of  nature"  (p.  178),  unless  we 
assume  that  this  advance  in  itself  necessitates  a  non-uniform  mani- 
fold,21 but  this  of  course  begs  the  question.  Nor  again  does  uni- 
formity of  the  manifold  necessarily  follow  from  that  of  the  momen- 
tary spaces  and  timeless  spaces  of  p.  194 ;  for  these  may  be  no  more 
than  mathematical  or  methodological  devices. 

But  difficulties  on  points  of  detail  such  as  those  I  have  mentioned 
are  inevitable ;  even  were  they  far  more  serious,  still  Dr.  Whitehead's 
work  constitutes  a  distinct  advance  in  the  discussion  of  ontology; 
and  if  it  could  be  supplemented  from  the  strictly  philosophic  stand- 
point, we  should  be  much  nearer  a  lasting  and  satisfactory  realism. 
There  appear  to  me  to  be  two  marked  parallel  tendencies  in  current 
philosophy — one  towards  absolutism,  the  other  towards  realism.  But 
absolutism  has  for  long  been  misrepresented  and  therefore  misun- 
derstood; it  has  been  presented  at  once  as  too  subjective  and  too 
abstract.22  I  do  not  see  anything  which  prevents  realism  from  tak- 
ing its  place  within  a  system  of  absolute  idealism  fuller  and  deeper 
than  any  yet  conceived.  Vestigia  nulla  retrorsum,  some  one  will  say ; 
but  then  the  absolute  is  not  a  cave.  Even  if  it  were,  we  are  in  it 
already. 

J.  B.  TURNER. 

LIVEBPOOL,  ENGLAND. 

A  BEHAVIORISTIC  ACCOUNT  OF  THE  SIGNIFICANT 

SYMBOL 

THE  statement  I  wish  to  present  rests  upon  the  following  as- 
sumptions, which  I  can  do  no  more  than  state:     I  assume, 
provisionally,  the  hypothesis  of  the  physical  sciences,  that  physical 
objects  and  the  physical  universe  may  be  analyzed  into  a  complex 
of  physical  corpuscles.    I  assume  that  the  objects  of  immediate  ex- 

21  As  distinct,  i.e.,  from  the  systems.  There  must  be  some  distinction,  other- 
wise we  should  have  systems  of  measurement  with  nothing  to  measure;  "  a 
measure-system  measures  something  inherent  in  nature"  (p.  196). 

22 ' '  The  Absolutism  which  comes  in  for  rebuke  at  the  hands  of  pluralist 
critics  is  a  fiction  of  their  own  imagination. ' '  Radhakrishnan,  Eeign  of  Eeligion 
in  Philosophy,  p.  407. 


158  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOP11  Y 

perience  exist   in  relationship  to  the  biologic  and  social  individuals 
whose  environments  they  make  up.     This  relationship  involves  on 
the  one  hand  the  selection  through  the  sensitivities  and  reactions  of 
the  living  forms  of  those  elements  that  go  to  make  up  the  object. 
On  the  other  hand   these  objects  affect  the  plants  and  animals, 
whose  natures  are  responsible  for  them  as  objects,  e.g.,  food  e\ 
as  an  immediate  experience  in  its  relation  to  the  individuals  that 
eat  it.     There  is  no  such   thing  as   food   apart   from   such    indi- 
viduals.   The  selection  of  the  characters  which  go  to  make  up  food 
is  a  function  of  living  individuals.    The  effect  of  this  food  upon  the 
living  individuals  is  what  we  call  adaptation  of  the  form  to  the 
environment  or  its  opposite.    Whatever  may  be  said  of  a  mechanic 
cal  universe  of  ultimate  physical  particles,  the  lines  that  are  drawn  1 
about  objects  in  experience  are  drawn  by  the  attitudes  and  conduct  * 
of  individual  living  forms.     Apart  from  such  an  experience  in- 
volving both  the  form  and  its  environment,  such  objects  do  not 
exist. 

On  the  other  hand  these  objects  exist  objectively,  as  they  J 
are  in  immediate  experience.  The  relation  of  objects  making  up 
an  environment  to  the  plants  and  the  animals  in  no  sense  renders 
these  objects  subjective.  What  are  termed  the  natures  of  objects  are 
in  the  objects,  as  are  their  so-called  sensuous  qualities,  but  these 
natures  are  not  in  the  objects  either  as  external  or  internal  rela- 
tions, they  are  of  the  very  essence  of  the  objects,  and  become  rela- 
tions only  in  the  thought  process.  The  so-called  sensuous  qualities 
exist  also  in  the  objects,  but  only  in  their  relations  to  the  sensitive 
organisms  whose  environments  they  form. 

The  causal  effect  of  the  living  organisms  on  their  environment  1 
in  creating  objects  is  as  genuine  as  the  effect  of  the  environment  » 
upon  the  living  organism.  A  digestive  tract  creates  food  as  truly 
as  the  advance  of  a  glacial  cap  wipes  out  some  animals  or  selects 
others  which  can  grow  warm  coats  of  hair.  An  animal's  sensitive- 
ness to  a  particular  character  in  ai«.  object  gives  the  object  in  its 
relation  to  the  animal  a  peculiar  nature.  Where  there  is  sensi- 
tiveness to  two  or  more  different  characters  of  the  object,  answer- 
ing to  reactions  that  conflict  and  thus  inhibit  each  other,  the  object 
is  in  so  far  analyzed.  Thus  the  width  of  a  stream  would  be  isolated 
from  the  other  characters  of  the  stream  through  the  inhibition  of  the 
animal's  tendency  to  jump  over  it.  In  the  immediate  experience  in 
which  the  animal  organism  and  its  environment  are  involved,  these 
characters  of  the  objects  and  the  inhibited  reactions  that  answer  to 
them  are  there  or  exist,  as  characters,  though  as  yet  they  have  no 
significance  nor  are  they  located  in  minds  or  consciousnesses. 

Amon«z  objects  in  the  immediate  experience  of  animals  are  the 


THE  SIGNIFICANT  SYMBOL  159 

different  parts  of  their  own  organisms,  which  have  different  char- 
acters from  those  of  other  objects — especially  hedonic  characters, 
and  those  of  stresses  and  excitements — but  characters  not  referred 
to  selves  until  selves  arise  in  experience.  They  are  only  accident- 
ally private,  i.e.,  necessarily  confined  to  the  experience  of  single 
individuals.  If — after  the  fashion  of  the  Siamese  Twins — two 
organisms  were  so  joined  that  the  same  organ  were  connected 
•with  the  central  nervous  system  of  each,  each  would  have  the  same 
painful  or  pleasurable  object  in  experience.  A  toothache  or  a 
pleased  palate  are  objects  for  a  single  individual  for  reasons  that 
are  not  essentially  different  from  those  which  make  the  flame  of  a 
match  scratched  in  a  room  in  which  there  is  only  one  individual 
an  object  only  for  that  individual.  It  is  not  the  exclusion  of  an 
object  from  the  experience  in  which  others  are  involved  which 
renders  it  subjective ;  it  is  rendered  subjective  by  being  referred  by 
an  individual  to  his  self,  when  selves  have  arisen  in  the  development 
of  conduct.  Exclusive  experiences  are  peculiarly  favorable  for  such 
reference,  but  characteristics  of  objects  for  every  one  may  be  so  re- 
ferred in  mental  processes. 

Among  objects  that  exist  only  for  separate  individuals  are  so- 
called  images.  They  are  there,  but  are  not  necessarily  located  in 
space.  They  do  enter  into  the  structure  of  things,  as  notably  on ' 
the  printed  page,  or  in  the  hardness  of  a  distant  object ;  and  in  hal- 
lucinations they  may  be  spatially  located.  They  are  dependent 
for  their  existence  upon  conditions  in  the  organism — especially 
those  of  the  central  nervous  system — as  are  other  objects  in  ex- 
perience such  as  mountains  and  chairs.  When  referred  to  the 
self  they  become  memory  images,  or  those  of  a  creative  imagina- 
tion, but  they  are  not  mental  or  spiritual  stuff. 

Conduct  is  the  sum  of  the  reactions  of  living  beings  to  their  ' 
environments,  especially  to  the  objects  which  their  relation  to  the  ' 
environment  has  "cut  out  of  it,"  to  use  a  Bergsonian  phrase. 
Among  these  objects  are  certain  which  are  of  peculiar  importance 
to  which  I  wish  to  refer,  viz.,  other  living  forms  which  belong  to 
the  same  group.  The  attitudes  and  early  indications  of  actions 
of  these  forms  are  peculiarly  important  stimuli,  and  to  extend  a 
Wundtian  term  may  be  called  "gestures."  These  other  living 
forms  in  the  group  to  which  the  organism  belongs  may  be  called 
social  objects  and  exist  as  such  before  selves  come  into  existence. 
These  gestures  call  out  definite,  and  in  all  highly  organized  forms, 
partially  predetermined  reactions,  such  as  those  of  sex,  of  parenthood, 
of  hostility,  and  possibly  others,  such  as  the  so-called  herd  instincts. 
In  so  far  as  these  specialized  reactions  are  present  in  the  nature 
of  individuals,  they  tend  to  arise  whenever  the  appropriate  stimu- 


160  JOURNAL  OF  PU1LOSOP1I  Y 

lu.s,  or  gesture  calls  them  out.  If  an  individual  uses  such  a  gesture, 
and  he  is  affected  by  it  as  another  individual  is  affected  by  it,  he 
responds  or  tends  to  respond  to  his  own  social  stimulus,  as  another 
individual  would  respond.  A  notable  instance  of  this  is  in  the 
song,  or  vocal  gesture  of  birds.  The  vocal  gesture  is  of  peculiar 
importance  because  it  reacts  upon  the  individual  who  makes  it 
in  the  same  fashion  that  it  reacts  upon  another,  but  this  is  also  true 
in  a  less  degree  of  those  of  one's  own  gestures  that  he  can  see  or  feel. 

The  self  arises  in  conduct,  when  the  individual  becomes  a  social 
object  in  experience  to  himself.  This  takes  place  when  the  indi- 
vidual assumes  the  attitude  or  uses  the  gesture  which  another  indi- 
vidual would  use  and  responds  to  it  himself,  or  tends  so  to  re- 
spond. It  is  a  development  that  arises  gradually  in  the  life  of 
the  infant  and  presumably  arose  gradually  in  the  life  of  the  race. 
It  arises  in  the  life  of  the  infant  through  what  is  unfortunately 
called  imitation,  and  finds  its  expression  in  the  normal  play  life 
of  young  children.  In  the  process  the  child  gradually  becomes  a 
social  being  in  his  own  experience,  and  he  acts  toward  himself  in  a 
manner  analogous  to  that  in  which  he  acts  toward  others.  Espec- 
ially he  talks  to  himself  as  he  talks  to  others  and  in  keeping  up 
this  conversation  in  the  inner  forum  constitutes  the  field  which  is 
called  that  of  mind.  Then  those  objects  and  experiences  which  be- 
long to  his  own  body,  those  images  which  belong  to  his  own  past, 
become  part  of  this  self. 

In  the  behavior  of  forms  lower  than  man,  we  find  one  individual 
indicating  objects  to  other  forms,  though  without  what  we  term 
signification.  The  hen  that  pecks  at  the  angleworn  is  directly 
though  without  intention  indicating  it  to  the  chicks.  The  animal 
in  a  herd  that  scents  danger,  in  moving  away  indicates  to  the  other 
members  of  the  herd  the  direction  of  safety  and  puts  them  in  the 
attitude  of  scenting  the  same  danger.  The  hunting  dog  points 
to  the  hidden  bird.  The  lost  lamb  that  bleats,  and  the  child  that 
cries  each  points  himself  out  to  his  mother.  All  of  these  gestures, 
to  the  intelligent  observer,  are  significant  symbols,  but  they  are 
none  of  them  significant  to  the  forms  that  make  them. 

In  what  does  this  significance  consist  in  terms  of  a  behavioristic 
psychology?  A  summary  answer  would  be  that  the  gesture  not 
only  actually  brings  the  stimulus-object  into  the  range  of  the  re- 
actions of  other  forms,  but  that  the  nature  of  the  object  is  also 
indicated;  especially  do  we  imply  in  the  term  significance  that  the 
individual  who  points  out  indicates  the  nature  to  himself.  But 
it  is  not  enough  that  he  should  indicate  this  meaning — whatever 
meaning  is — as  it  exists  for  himself  alone,  but  that  he  should  indi- 
cate that  meaning  as  it  exists  for  the  other  to  whom  he  is  pointing 


THE  SIGNIFICANT  SYMBOL  161 

it  out.  The  widest  use  of  the  term  implies  that  he  indicates  the 
meaning  to  any  other  individual  to  whom  it  might  be  pointed  out 
in  the  same  situation.  In  so  far  then  as  the  individual  takes  the 
attitude  of  another  toward  himself,  and  in  some  sense  arouses  in 
himself  the  tendency  to  the  action,  which  his  conduct  calls  out  in 
the  other  individual,  he  will  have  indicated  to  himself  the  meaning 
of  the  gesture.  This  implies  a  definition  of  meaning — that  it  is  an 
indicated  reaction  which  the  object  may  call  out.  When  we  find 
that  we  have  adjusted  ourselves  to  a  comprehensive  set  of  reactions 
toward  an  object  we  feel  that  the  meaning  of  the  object  is  ours. 
But  that  the  meaning  may  be  ours,  it  is  necessary  that  we  should  be 
able  to  regard  ourselves  as  taking  this  attitude  of  adjustment  to 
response.  We  must  indicate  to  ourselves  not  only  the  object  but 
also  the  readiness  to  respond  in  certain  ways  to  the  object,  and 
this  indication  must  be  made  in  the  attitude  or  role  of  the  other 
individual  to  whom  it  is  pointed  out  or  to  whom  it  may  be  pointed 
out.  If  this  is  not  the  case  it  has  not  that  common  property  which 
is  involved  in  significance.  It  is  through  the  ability  to  be  the  other 
at  the  same  time  that  he  is  himself  that  the  symbol  becomes  signifi- 
cant. The  common  statement  of  this  is  that  we  have  in  mind,  what 
we  indicate  to  another  that  he  shall  do.  In  giving  directions,  we 
give  the  direction  to  ourselves  at  the  same  time  that  we  give  it  to  an- 
other. We  assume  also  his  attitude  of  response  to  our  requests,  as 
an  individual  to  whom  the  direction  has  the  same  signification  in 
his  conduct  that  it  has  to  ourselves. 

But  signification  is  not  confined  to  the  particular  situation 
within  which  an  indication  is  given.  It  acquires  universal  mean- 
ing. Even  if  the  two  are  the  only  ones  involved,  the  form  in  which 
it  is  given  is  universal — it  would  have  the  same  meaning  to  any 
other  who  might  find  himself  in  the  same  position.  How  does  this 
generalization  arise?  From  the  behavioristic  standpoint  it  must 
take  place  through  the  individual  generalizing  himself  in  his  atti- 
tude of  the  other.  We  are  familiar  enough  with  the  undertaking, 
in  social  and  moral  instruction  to  children  and  to  those  who  are 
not  children.  A  child  acquires  the  sense  of  property  through 
taking  what  may  be  called  the  attitude  of  the  generalized  other. 
Those  attitudes  which  all  assume  in  given  conditions  and  over 
against  the  same  objects,  become  for  him  attitudes  which  every 
one  assumes.  In  taking  the  role  which  is  common  to  all,  he  finds 
himself  speaking  to  himself  and  to  others  with  the  authority  of  the 
group.  These  attitudes  become  axiomatic.  The  generalization  is 
simply  the  result  of  the  identity  of  responses.  Indeed  it  is  only 
as  he  has  in  some  sense  amalgamated  the  attitudes  of  the  different 
roles  in  which  he  has  addressed  himself  that  he  acquires  the  unity 


162  JOURNAL  OF  PHlLOSOl'll  Y 

of  personality.  The  "me"  that  he  addresses  is  constantly  varied. 
It  answers  to  the  changing  play  of  impulse,  but  the  group  solidar- 
ity, especially  in  its  uniform  restrictions,  gives  him  the  unity  of 
universality.  This  I  take  to  be  the  sole  source  of  the  universal. 
It  quickly  passes  the  bounds  of  the  specific  group.  It  is  the  vox 
populi,  vox  dei,  the  "voice  of  men  and  of  angels."  Education  and 
varied  experience  refine  out  of  it  what  is  provincial,  and  leave 
"what  is  true  for  all  men  at  all  times."  From  the  first,  its  form 
is  universal,  for  differences  of  the  different  attitudes  of  others  wear 
their  peculiarities  away.  In  the  play  period,  however,  before  the 
child  has  reached  that  of  competitive  games — in  which  he  seeks 
to  pit  his  own  acquired  self  against  others — in  the  play  period 
this  process  is  not  fully  carried  out  and  the  child  is  as  varied  as 
his  varying  moods ;  but  in  the  game  he  sees  himself  in  terms  of  the 
group  or  the  gang  and  speaks  with  a  passion  for  rules  and  stand- 
ards. Its  social  advantage  and  even  necessity  makes  this  approach 
to  himself  imperative.  He  must  see  himself  as  the  whole  group 
sees  him.  This  again  has  passed  under  the  head  of  passive  imita- 
tion. But  it  is  not  in  uniform  attitudes  that  universality  appears 
as  a  recognized  factor  in  either  inner  or  outer  behavior.  It  is  found 
rightly  in  thought  and  thought  is  the  conversation  of  this  general- 
ized other  with  the  self. 

The  significant  symbol  is  then  the  gesture,  the  sign,  the  word 
which  is  addressed  to  the  self  when  it  is  addressed  to  another  indi- 
vidual, and  is  addressed  to  another,  in  form  to  all  other  indi- 
viduals, when  it  is  addressed  to  the  self. 

Signification  has,  as  we  have  seen,  two  references,  one  to  the  thing 
indicated,  and  the  other  to  the  response,  to  the  instance  and  to  the 
meaning  or  idea.  It  denotes  and  connotes.  When  the  symbol  is  used 
for  the  one,  it  is  a  name.  When  it  is  used  for  the  other,  it  is  a  con- 
cept. But  it  neither  denotes  nor  connotes  except,  when  in  form  at 
least,  denotation  and  connotation  are  addressed  both  to  a  self  and  to 
others,  when  it  is  in  a  universe  of  discourse  that  is  oriented  with  re- 
ference to  a  self.  If  the  gesture  simply  indicates  the  object  to  another, 
it  has  no  meaning  to  the  individual  who  makes  it,  nor  does  the  re- 
sponse which  the  other  individual  carries  out  become  a  meaning  to 
him,  unless  he  assumes  the  attitude  of  having  his  attention  directed 
by  an  individual  to  whom  it  has  a  meaning.  Then  he  takes  his  own 
response  to  be  the  meaning  of  the  indication.  Through  this  sympa- 
thetic placing  of  themselves  in  each  other's  roles,  and  finding  thus  in 
their  own  experiences  the  responses  of  the  others,  what  would  other- 
wise be  an  unintelligent  gesture,  acquires  just  the  value  which  is 
connoted  by  signification,  both  in  its  specific  application  and  in  its 
universality. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  163 

It  should  be  added  that  in  so  far  as  thought — that  inner  conver- 
sation in  which  objects  as  stimuli  are  both  separated  from  and  related 
to  their  responses — is  identified  with  consciousness,  that  is  in  so  far 
as  consciousness  is  identified  with  awareness,  it  is  the  result  of  this 
development  of  the  self  in  experience.  The  other  prevalent  significa- 
tion of  consciousness  is  found  simply  in  the  presence  of  objects  in 
experience.  With  the  eyes  shut  we  can  say  we  are  no  longer  conscious 
of  visual  objects.  If  the  condition  of  the  nervous  system  or  certain 
tracts  in  it,  cancels  the  relation  of  individual  and  his  environment, 
he  may  be  said  to  lose  consciousness  or  some  portion  of  it ;  i.e.,  some 
objects  or  all  of  them  pass  out  of  experience  for  this  individual.  Of 
peculiar  interest  is  the  disappearance  of  a  painful  object,  e.g.,  an 
aching  tooth  under  a  local  anesthetic.  A  general  anesthetic  shuts  out 
all  objects. 

As  above  indicated  analysis  takes  place  through  the  conflict  of 
responses  which  isolates  separate  features  of  the  object  and  both  sep- 
arates them  from  and  relates  them  to  their  responses,  i.e.,  their  mean- 
ings. The  response  becomes  a  meaning,  when  it  is  indicated  by  a 
generalized  attitude  both  to  the  self  and  to  others.  Mind,  which  is  a 
process  within  which  this  analysis  and  its  indications  take  place,  lies 
in  a  field  of  conduct  between  a  specific  individual  and  the  environ- 
ment, in  which  the  individual  is  able,  through  the  generalized  attitude 
he  assumes,  to  make  use  of  symbolic  gestures,  i.e.,  terms,  which  are 
significant  to  all  including  himself. 

While  the  conflict  of  reactions  takes  place  within  the  individual, 
the  analysis  takes  place  in  the  object.  Mind  is  then  a  field  that  is  not 
confined  to  the  individual  much  less  is  located  in  a  brain.  Signifi- 
cance belongs  to  things  in  their  relations  to  individuals.  It  does  not 
lie  in  mental  processes1  which  are  enclosed  within  individuals. 

GEORGE  H.  MEAD. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  CHICAGO. 


The  Analysis  of  Mind.    BERTBAND  RUSSELL.    London :  George  Allen 
and  Unwin.    New  York :  The  Macmillan  Co.    1921.    Pp.  310. 
The  book  deals  with  that  conception  of  the  nature  of  mind  which 
is  involved  in  regarding  physical  objects  as  constructs  of  appearances. 
Thus  it  is  in  effect  the  logical  sequel  to  views  expressed  by  the  author 
in  his  Lowell  Lectures,  and  in  it  he  has  given  us  what  is  the  most  com- 
plete and  balanced  statement  to  date  of  the  results  of  his  philosophic 
method. 

Mr.  Russell's  central  thesis  is  that  all  psychical  phenomena  are 
built  up  out  of  sensations  and  images,  and  nothing  else.    This  involves 


164  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

• 

a  departure  from  his  own  piwiou>  theory  "that  the  essence  of  every- 
thing mental  is  a  certain  quite  peculiar  something  called  'conscious- 
ness','* and  more  specifically  a  revision  of  his  doctrine  of  knowledge 
by  acquaintance.  Moreover  since  the  physical  as  well  as  the  psychical 
is  a  construction  of  appearances,  his  most  fundamental  systematic 
problem  is  that  of  distinguishing  between  mind  and  matter.  In  lec- 
ture I  (Recent  criticisms  of  "consciousness"),  and  lecture  VI  (Intro- 
spection), he  shows  that  this  must  not  be  thought  of  as  a  substantial 
dualism.  His  general  position  is  a  monism  whose  ideal  is  "that  funda- 
mental science  .  .  .  the  true  metaphysic,  in  which  mind  and  matter 
alike  are  seen  to  be  constructed  out  of  a  neutral  stuff"  (p.  287). 
This  ultimate  stuff,  which  presumably  consists  of  the  multiplicity 
of  appearances,  is  the  common  subject-matter  both  of  physics  and 
psychology.  But  the  latter  science  deals  with  it  by  means  of  causal 
laws  which  have  two  special  characteristics.  In  the  first  place,  all 
psychical  phenomena  are  said  to  posseas  "subjectivity."  To  thi< 
term  a  very  special  meaning  attaches,  which  may  be  made  clear  as 
follows.  Every  particular  of  the  kind  considered  by  physics  may 
on  the  one  hand  be  regarded  as  a  member  of  a  group  constituting 
a  thing,  as  explained  in  Mr.  Russell 's  Lowell  Lectures  and  elsewhere, 
as  well  as  in  the  present  work ;  on  the  other  hand  it  may  be  a  mem- 
ber of  a  group  constituting  a  perspective,  a  group  of  which  in  turn 
make  up  a  "biography."  The  most  significant  purely  logical  mark 
of  a  biography  is  that  it  possesses  a  linear  time-order,  that  is,  it  is 
a  group  of  entities  which  have  direct  time-relations  (simultaneous 
with,  before,  after)  with  respect  to  any  one  of  themselves,  as  opposed 
to  the  time  order  of  the  physical  universe.  The  "local  time"  of  the 
theory  of  relativity  occurs  in  biographies.  And  it  is  such  a  classi- 
fication, which  is  also  called  classification  by  "passive  places,"  that 
Mr.  Russell  understands  as  the  essence  of  subjectivity.  But  this  is 
not  a  complete  designation  of  the  nature  of  psychical  phenomena, 
for  many  such  biographies  will  have  nothing  to  do  with  mind.  A 
photographic  plate  might  have  a  biography  in  this  sense.  An  addi- 
tional determining  factor  is  needed  for  the  specification  of  mind, 
and  this  is  provided  by  "mnemic  causation."  This  means  that  the 
nature  of  our  experience  of  any  event  is  not  wholly  caused  by  the 
immediate,  present  occurrence  of  that  event,  but  also  by  its  past 
occurrences  in  our  experience.  "This  characteristic  is  embodied  in 
the  saying  'the  burnt  child  dreads  the  fire'.  The  burn  may  have 
left  no  visible  traces,  yet  it  modifies  the  reaction  of  the  child  in  the 
presence  of  the  fire"  (p.  77).  While  Mr.  Russell  agrees  that  it  is 
probable  that  such  phenomena  can  be  explained  by  regarding  the 
results  of  experience  as  being  embodied  in  modifications  of  the  brain 
and  nerves,  he  points  out  that  this  is  a  theory  only,  and  prefers  to 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  165 

operate  with  the  bare  formulation  of  the  observed  facts.  Thus  "the 
two  most  essential  characteristics  of  the  causal  laws  which  would 
naturally  be  called  psychological  are  subjectivity  and  mnemic  causa- 
tion" (p.  307). 

The  bulk  of  the  book  is  taken  up  with  the  detailed  elaboration  of 
the  theory  above  outlined  in  terms  in  its  application  to  various 
psychological  and  epistemological  conceptions.  A  perception  is  the 
appearance  of  an  object  from  a  place  where  there  is  a  brain.  Such 
appearances  undergo  distortion  owing  to  the  intervening  media  of 
the  organic  structure,  and  also  stand  in  the  nexus  of  mnemic  causa- 
tion. Sensations  are  the  non-mnemic  core  of  perceptions,  and  are 
the  elements  common  to  both  the  mental  and  physical  worlds. 
Images  differ  from  sensations  in  that  their  causation  is  wholly 
mnemic,  that  is,  they  arise  from  past  experience.  Belief,  which  is 
"the  central  problem  in  the  analysis  of  mind"  (p.  231)  is  analyzed 
into  content,  which  is  a  complex  of  images  and  sensations,  and  a 
specific  feeling  called  believing,  which  is  "presumably  a  complex 
sensation  demanding  analysis"  (p.  251).  In  terms  of  belief  are 
defined  memory,  expectation,  and  assent,  the  differences  between 
them  being  not  an  affair  of  content,  but  arising  out  of  the  three 
kinds  of  belief-feeling  which  may  attach  to  any  complex  of  images. 
Imagination  consists  of  images  without  belief.  The  study  of  belief 
also  leads  to  a  formal  theory  of  truth  and  falsehood.  Emotions  and 
will  are  discussed  in  consonance  with  the  general  position  of  the 
book,  emotions  being  regarded  as  serial  patterns  of  sensations  and 
images.  Desire  is  treated  as  being  a  sort  of  analogue  to  force  in 
physics.  Instinct  and  habit  are  also  considered.  The  meaning  of 
words,  and  also  that  of  images  is  explained  largely  with  reference 
to  mnemic  causation.  In  dealing  with  general  ideas  we  are  given  a 
very  valuable  analysis  of  vagueness  and  the  generic  image.  The 
discussion  of  introspection  is  notable  for  its  penetration  and  lucidity. 
In  the  final  lecture  there  is  presented  a  theory  of  consciousness.  An 
interesting  point  is  the  philosophical  assimilation  of  the  psycho- 
analytic method.  At  the  close  of  the  book  is  an  analytic  table  of 
contents  which  is  remarkable  only  for  its  lack  of  value. 

The  whole  work,  which  displays  its  author's  constructive  insight 
and  analytic  power  to  the  best  advantage,  is  of  great  methodolog- 
ical interest  as  a  thoroughgoing  reconstitution  of  structural  psy- 
chology. Mr.  Russell  rejects  behaviorism  as  an  ultimate  account  of 
the  nature  of  mind,  because  it  is  based  on  a  faulty  philosophy  of 
physics,  which  fails  to  regard  the  universe  as  fundamentally  a  multi- 
plicity of  particulars.  Perhaps  the  weakest  spot  is  the  treatment 
of  belief-feelings,  which  are  somewhat  dogmatically  said  to  consist 
of  complex  sensations,  although  no  attempt  is  made  to  analyze  these 


166  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

complexes.  This,  Imwcvrr,  is  at  the  worst  an  error  of  omission, 
and  throughout  w<-  find  an  accuracy  in  defining  and  a  directness 
in  attacking  p'-miim-  problems  not  usual  in  work  of  this  character. 
The  cut  in-  discussion  will  be  welcomed,  not  only  as  the  latest  author- 
itative exposition  of  a  point  of  view  which  has  become  very  in- 
fluential, but  also  as  a  highly  significant  contribution  to  modern 
philosophy. 

JAMES  L.  MURSELL. 
COLUMBUS,  OHIO. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  AMERICAN  JOURNAL  OF  PSYCHOLOGY,  July,  1921. 
An  Experimental  Investigation  of  the  Positive  After-Image  in  Audi- 
tion (pp.  305-325).  HOMER  GUY  Bisnop.-There  is  no  positive  after 
image  of  tone  similar  to  the  nature  of  the  visual  after-image.  The 
Influence  of  Color  upon  Mental  and  Motor  Efficiency  (pp.  326-356)  : 
SIDNEY  L.  PREssEY.-Experimental  evidence  suggests  that  there  is  a 
slowing  up  of  mental  .work  under  dim  light,  but  hues  aside  from 
brightness  show  no  effect.  Bibliography.  The  Nature  of  the  Affec- 
tive Judgment  in  the  Method  of  Paired  Comparisons  (pp.  357-369)  : 
M.  YoKOYAMA.-The  method  of  paired  comparisons  can  no  longer  be 
considered  as  a  typical  laboratory  setting  for  the  study  of  affections. 
A  Study  in  Logical  Memory  (pp.  370-403) :  SARAH  D.  MACKAY 
AusnN.-After  from  two  to  four  weeks  repetitions  of  both  logical 
and  nonsense  material  proved  of  greater  value  than  cumulative 
repetitions.  In  Aid  of  Introspection  (pp.  404-414) :  HORACE  BID- 
WELL  ENGLiSH.-Introspection  is  approved  as  a  psychological  method. 
Several  rules  are  given.  "Any  one  with  a  good  memory  and  a  sincere 
desire  to  improve  can  learn  to  introspect  in  a  way  which  will  be  of 
distinct  scientific  usefulness."  Minor  Studies  from  the  Psychological 
Laboratory  of  Cornell  University.  An  Experimental  Study  of  Cuta- 
neous Imagery  (pp.  415-420) :  CATHERINE  BRADDOCK.-Cutaneous 
images  come  up  rarely  if  ever.  The  Integration  of  Punctiform  Cold 
and  Pressure  (pp.  421-424)  :  S.  TuNQ.-The  simultaneous  stimula- 
tion of  pressure  and  cold  spots  was  felt  as  wet-cold.  The  H< 
Color-Blindness  Apparatus  and  the  Normal  Equation  (pp.  425-428)  : 
M.  WINFIELD  AND  C.  STRONG.-Variation  from  the  normality  in  color 
combination  approvals  is  insufficient  evidence  for  normality  an  1 
abnormality.  The  After-Effect  of  Seen  Movement  When  the  Whole 
Visual  Field  is  filed  by  a  Moving  Stimulus  (pp.  429-441) :  WELLING- 
TON A.  THALMAN.-The  after-effect  is  observed  when  the  whole  visual 
field  is  filled  by  an  objective  moving  stimulus  the  chief  conditioning 
factor  of  which  is  duration.  Book  Revieirs:  J.  B.  Pratt,  The  religious 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  167 

consciousness:  a  psychological  study:  E.  S.   AMES.     S.   Bernfeld, 

Da-s  jiidisohe  Volk  und  seine  Jugend:     S.  FELDMAN.     A  Note  on, 

"Vocality"  (pp.  446-447)  :  GILBERT  J.  RICH.    Consciousness  in  the 

Siamese  Twins:  E.  G.  B. 

Dewey,  Evelyn.  The  Dalton  Laboratory  Plan.  New  York:  E.  P. 
Button  &  Co.  1922.  Pp.  vii  -f  173. 

Leon,  Xavier.  Fichte  et  son  Temps.  Vol.  I.  Etablissement  et  Pred- 
ication de  la  Doctrine  de  la  Liberte;  Le  Vie  de  Fichte  jusqu'au 
depart  d'lena  (1762-1799).  Paris:  Armand  Colin.  1922.  Pp. 
xvi  -f  652.  30  fr. 

McCall,  William  A.  How  to  Measure  in  Education.  New  York: 
The  Macmillan  Co.  1922.  Pp.  xii  -f  416. 

Moore,  Jared  Sparks.  The  Foundations  of  Psychology.  Princeton, 
N.  J. :  University  Press.  1922.  Pp.  xix  -f  239.  $3. 

Poyer,  Georges.  Les  Problemes  Generaux  de  THeredite  psycholo- 
gique.  Paris:  Felix  Alcan.  1921.  Pp.  302.  15  fr. 

Eeyburn,  Hugh  A.  The  Ethical  Theory  of  Hegel:  A  Study  of  the 
Philosophy  of  Right.  Oxford:  The  Clarendon  Press.  1921. 

Pp.  xx  -f  268. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

A  meeting  of  the  Aristotelian  Society  was  held  in  London  on 
January  16,  Dr.  F.  C.  S.  Schiller,  President,  in  the  chair.  A  paper 
on  "Plato's  Theory  of  et'/cacrta"  was  presented  by  Mr.  H.  J.  Paton. 
In  Plato 's  account  of  the  Line  and  the  Cave  in  the  Republic  he  dis- 
tinguishes two  sub-divisions  of  opinion  (el/caa-ia  or  intuition  and 
Trwrri?  or  belief)  and  two  sub-divisions  of  knowledge  (  Siavoia  or 
mathematical  reasoning  and  vowa-is  or  philosophical  reasoning). 
This  must  be  understood  as  implying  a  difference  of  objects  in  each 
of  the  four  sub-divisions,  just  as  the  objects  of  opinion  and  knowl- 
edge are  different — the  changing  individuals  as  opposed  to  the  un- 
changing universals.  The  parallelism  or  analogy  between  the  ob- 
jects of  the  two  main  divisions  and  those  of  the  sub-divisions  is  meant 
to  be  taken  seriously  throughout.  In  particular  the  objects  of  the 
elxaa-ia  or  intuition  are  the  many  appearances,  whether  given  in 
what  we  call  sense  or  memory  or  imagination,  from  which  we  pass 
to  the  objects  of  TTIO-TK  or  belief — the  solid  bodies  of  the  ordinary 
consciousness  and  of  science,  things  relatively  permanent  and  re- 
latively intelligible  in  comparison  with  their  many  appearances, 


168  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOI'Jl  Y 

although  e!ian^in(.r  and  unintelligible  in  comparison  \\ith  the  really 
permanent  and  really  intelligible  fiSij  or  universals.  It  is  a  com- 
plete prror  to  regard  ciKao-ta  and  its  objects  as  of  no  metaphysical 
importance,  and  an  und'Tstandin:/  of  the  nature  of  this  section  is 
mres-ary  if  \v«>  are  to  grasp  Plato's  u'fneral  theory  of  knowledge. 
Even  Plato's  theory  that  art  must  be  classified  under  this  first 
cognitive  activity  of  the  spirit  is  in  iis  essence  sound  in  spite  of 
the  fact  that  some  of  the  conclusions  which  he  derived  from  it  were 
mistaken. 

The  annual  meeting  of  the  Western  Division  of  the  American 
Philosophical  Association  this  year  will  be  held  at  the  University 
of  Nebraska,  Lincoln,  Nebraska,  on  Friday  and  Saturday,  April 
14  and  15.  As  usual,  members  will  have  opportunity  to  present 
papers — not  exceeding  twenty  minutes  in  length — on  any  topics  of 
their  selection.  It  is  proposed  however  that  one  afternoon  session 
be  devoted  to  Logical  Aspects  of  Critical  Realism  with  Professor  A. 
W.  Moore  as  leader  of  the  discussion.  All  who  feel  especially  in- 
terested in  the  recent  volume,  Essays  in  Critical  Realism,  or  any 
of  its  problems,  are  invited  to  participate.  It  has  been  suggested  that 
the  papers  of  one  other  session  relate  to  the  problem  of  The  Nature 
of  the  Self,  the  topic  being  taken  broadly  as  covering  methodological 
aspects  of  the  Mind-Body  Problem,  especially  Interactionism  as  it 
has  recently  been  presented,  and  the  relations  of  Mechanism  and 
Teleology  as  pertaining  to  the  nature  of  the  self.  Should  the  papers 
offered  warrant  doing  so,  this  suggestion  will  be  followed  in  arrang- 
ing the  program.  A  list  of  references  on  this  subject  may  be  ob- 
tained from  the  Secretary,  Professor  G.  A.  Tawney,  University  of 
Cincinnati,  Cincinnati,  Ohio.  It  is  essential  that  the  Secretary  be 
notified  of  the  titles  at  an  early  date.  Abstracts  of  all  papers  to  be 
read  should  be  in  his  hands  not  later  than  April  7,  and  fifteen  to 
twenty  copies  of  each  abstract  would  be  highly  desirable  for  distribu- 
tion. 

A  group  of  scientific  men  and  women  from  Russia  now  living  in 
the  United  States  have  organized  themselves  into  the  "Russian 
Academic  Group. ' '  Their  first  annual  meeting  was  held  on  January 
12.  The  purpose  of  the  organization  is  threefold:  (1)  to  study  the 
social,  economic  and  industrial  problems  involved  in  the  develop- 
ment of  Russia;  (2)  to  bring  about  a  closer  contact  between  the 
scientific  and  educational  institutions  of  America  and  Russia;  and  (3) 
to  help  in  the  reconstruction  of  the  academic  life  of  the  Russian 
universities  and  to  bring  relief  to  their  faculties  and  students. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  7.  MARCH  30,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  METAPHYSICAL  STATUS  OF  SENSATIONS 

"  When  the  eye  and  the  appropriate  object  meet  together  and  give 
birth  to  whiteness  and  the  sensation  of  white,  which  could  not  have 
been  given  by  either  of  them  going  to  any  other,  then,  while  the  sight 
is  flowing  from  the  eye,  whiteness  proceeds  from  the  object  which  com- 
bine* in  producing  the  color;  and  so  the  eye  is  fulfilled  with  sight,  and 
sees,  and  becomes,  not  sight,  but  a  seeing  eye;  and  the  object  which 
combines  in  forming  the  color  is  fulfilled  with  whiteness,  and  becomes 
not  whiteness  but  white,  whether  wood  or  stone  or  whatever  the  object 
may  be  which  happens  to  be  colored  white.  And  this  is  true  of  all 
sensations,  hard,  warm,  and  the  like,  which  are  similarly  to  be  regarded, 
as  I  was  saying  before,  not  as  having  any  absolute  existence,  but  as 
being  all  of  them  generated  by  motion  in  their  intercourse  with  one 
another,  according  to  their  kinds."  (Plato:  Thecetetus,  pp.  156-157, 
Jowett's  translation.) 

IF  one  ever  needs  excuse  for  quoting  Plato,  it  would  do  in  this  case 
to  plead  that  the  doctrine  contained  in  the  passage  is  brilliant, 
thorough,  and  sound.  The  history  of  philosophy,  in  its  meandering 
course,  has  brought  forth  no  improvement  upon  the  statement  put 
into  the  mouth  of  Socrates  by  his  great  pupil.  One  need  not  agree 
with  all  the  positions  of  Plato  in  even  the  dialogue  from  which  the 
above  passage  was  taken  in  order  to  enter  fully  into  the 
proffered  analysis  of  the  metaphysical  status  of  sensations.  Socrates 
is  making  no  pretense  of  originating  a  new  doctrine :  he  is  expound- 
ing that  of  Protagoras.  Indeed  he  seems  to  accept  as  true  everything 
which  Protagoras  says  about  sensation,  except  that  it  is  knowledge. 
This  doctrine  of  sensation,  however  sound,  becomes,  when  coupled 
with  the  supposition  that  sensations  are  cognitive  of  the  world  be- 
yond, involved  in  grave  difficulties ;  and  the  followers  of  Protagoras 
through  the  centuries  are  responsible  for  all  the  copy-theories  of 
sensation  which  have  so  led  philosophy  astray.  But  in  this  present 
paper  there  will  be  no  occasion  to  discuss  knowledge;  rather  the 
effort  will  be  made  simply  to  comment  upon  and  compare  with  less 
satisfactory  modern  analyses  that  doctrine  of  the  nature  of  sensa- 
tions which  Protagoras  formulated,  Socrates  accepted,  and  Plato  so 
beautifully  put  into  words.  And  if  the  points  commented  upon 
seem  trivial  and  commonplace,  the  writer  might  reply  that  he  wishes 
they  were  so  well  understood  and  so  widely  taken  for  granted  that 

169 


170  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

further  restatement  would  be  unnecessary.  As  so  often  is  the  case, 
metaphysics  is  needed  only  because  there  is  so  much  bad  metaphysics. 

Sensation  is  a  natural  event  which  takes  place  in  the  world 
under  certain  ascertainable  conditions.  We  have  good  reason  to 
believe  that  objects  existed  long  before  they  were  perceived  by  even 
the  first  organisms  endowed  with  organs  sensitive  to  stimuli  from 
those  objects ;  and  we  have  good  reason  to  believe  that  a  catastrophic 
destruction  of  all  organisms  would  leave  those  objects  in  undisturbed 
existence.  Sensation  is  an  event  which  happens  in  its  setting,  but 
does  not  produce  nor  control  that  setting.  The  setting  consists, 
for  the  purposes  of  analysis,  of  three  significant  elements  or  aspects. 
First,  there  is  the  object  such  as  a  stone,  a  cloud,  a  bon-bon,  or  an 
open  fire  on  a  wintry  day.  Secondly,  there  is  the  animal  organism, 
with  its  end-organs  of  various  sorts,  end-organs  which  might  under 
different  circumstances  have  become  other  than  they  are  but  happen 
to  be  as  they  are,  end-organs  such  as  the  eye,  the  ear,  and  the  various 
special  structures  in  the  skin.  Thirdly,  there  is  the  medium  of  com- 
munication between  object  and  end-organ,  the  physical  contact 
and  pressure  of  the  stone  against  the  organ  of  touch,  the  vibrating 
ether  between  the  cloud  and  the  eye,  the  physical  contact  and  chem- 
ical change  which  ensues  when  the  bon-bon  is  dissolved  upon  the 
tongue,  or  the  air-waves  between  the  fire  and  the  organ  of  heat. 
We  know  more  about  the  structure  of  the  end-organs  than  did 
Plato,  and  also  about  the  mediums  by  which  objects  affect  the  end- 
organs.  But  Socrates  did  not  need  to  know  the  details  of  all  the 
species  of  processes  involved  in  sense-experience,  in  order  to  formu- 
late correctly  the  definition  of  the  subsuming  genus ;  and  he  allows 
adequately  for  the  growth  of  scientific  knowledge  when  he  says  that 
the  various  kinds  of  sensations  are  "generated  by  motion  in  their 
intercourse  with  one  another  according  to  their  kinds."  Perhaps 
no  loss  of  accuracy  in  discussing  sensations  will  result  if  vision  is 
selected  for  special  treatment;  for  similar  things  could  be  said 
about  all  other  kinds  of  sensations. 

The  absence  of  one  or  more  of  the  three  elements  of  the  setting 
in  which  sensations  occur  will  of  course  make  sensations  impossible.1 
A  dazzling  sun  may  shine  with  unparalleled  splendor  for  countless 
ages;  but  there  will  be  nothing  seen  unless  the  electro-magnetic 
vibrations  starting  out  from  it  chance  to  strike  upon  the  sensitive 
retina  of  some  physiological  organism.  A  strong  eye,  well  con- 

i  That  sensations  may  arise  under  other  conditions  can  not  of  coarse  be 
dogmatically  denied.  Yet  the  only  sensations  of  which  we  know  anything  are 
generated  in  the  way  here  discussed;  and  we  have  no  reason  for  believing  in 
any  others. 


THE  METAPHYSICAL  STATUS  OF  SENSATIONS     171 

structed  in  all  its  parts  and  properly  related  to  a  healthy  organism, 
may  search  the  uttermost  reaches  of  space ;  but  there  will  be  nothing 
seen  unless  there  is  some  object  within  the  radius  of  its  range  and 
some  unimpeded  physical  force  to  stimulate  the  eye.  In  a  world 
where  no  interactions  took  place  between  the  various  things  of  which 
that  world  might  be  composed,  there  would  be  no  sensations;  and 
even  in  a  world  where  the  requisite  interactions  take  place,  there 
must  yet  be  properly  formed  end-organs  before  those  influences  pro- 
duce sensations.  If  the  nature  of  the  object  or  the  nature  of  the 
medium  of  communication  were  changed,  it  might  well  be  that  the 
end-organ  would  have  to  go  through  compensating  changes  before 
sensations  would  once  more  occur;  and  any  change  in  an  end-organ 
beyond  a  very  slight  one  would  probably  forever  put  a  stop  to  sensa- 
tions through  it,  unless  the  other  elements  of  the  setting  were  altered 
or  those  elements  chanced  to  have  other  activities  formerly  uncon- 
nected with  sensation-processes  and  yet  suited  thereto  in  connection 
with  the  altered  end-organ. 

The  part  of  Plato's  doctrine  of  sensations  which  is  important  for 
metaphysics  and  logic  remains  to  be  noted.  There  is  no  suggestion 
in  Plato  that  sensations  are  a  new  sort  of  entity  which  half  conceals 
and  half  discloses  the  world  which  the  organism  faces — not  that  he 
specifically  denies  that  such  is  the  case,  but  that  such  a  consideration 
is  irrelevant  to  the  subject-matter  under  examination.  The  followers 
of  Protagoras  who  regarded  sensations  as  knowledge  might  well  be- 
come involved  in  such  a  distressing  problem.  But  not  Plato.  For 
him  sensations  are  not  cognitive,  and  there  is  no  need  of  determining 
whether  the  sensation  is  a  "copy"  of  anything  else.  A  sensation 
like  an  explosion  of  gunpowder  is  an  event,  with  natural  causes  and 
effects;  but  it  no  more  mirrors  the  conditions  of  its  occurrence  than 
an  explosion  mirrors  the  chemicals  and  the  spark  which  set  those 
chemicals  off.  The  sensation-process  is  a  complex  process,  in  which, 
by  virtue  of  the  total  situation  established  by  object,  medium,  and 
end-organ,  the  object  and  the  end-organ  are  temporarily  of  a  dif- 
ferent nature  than  before  the  situation  was  established.  That  is,  the 
eye  becomes  a  seeing  eye,  and  the  object  becomes  a  white  object. 
There  would  be  no  objection  to  calling  the  white  object  or  the  white 
alone  by  such  terms  as  idea,  impression,  or  psychic  state,  provided 
that  no  improper  inferences  were  drawn  from  that  term.  Neither 
the  white  object  nor  the  white  is  any  of  those  things,  however,  if  by 
those  terms  is  meant  a,  separate  and  distinct  existence.  The  object 
seen  is  the  object  which  was  really  there  before  it  was  seen,  even 
though  it  was  not  then  white  and  did  not  stand  in  the  situation  in 
which  it  later  came  to  stand.  There  seems  to  be  no  warrant  for 


172  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

calling  objects  white  unless  they  are  seen;  but  the  white  object  seen 
is  the  same  object  which  the  eye  for  some  reason  singles  out  from 
the  total  environment.  As  Plato  puts  it,  the  eye  becomes  a  seeing 
eye  and  the  object  becomes  a  white  object;  and  Plato  would  cor- 
rectly add  that  no  further  entity  or  existence  was  involved  in  the 
process.  The  same  eye  may  be  the  organ  of  many  different  sensa- 
tions in  which  the  same  object  is  seen  in  many  different  shapes  and 
colors;  for  the  same  object  seen  may  be  seen  by  the  same  eye  in 
many  different  positions  and  under  many  different  conditions.  And 
since  the  nature  of  a  sensation  depends  upon  the  total  situation  of 
object,  medium,  and  end-organ,  the  nature  of  successive  sensations 
will  vary.  No  sensation  "grasps"  the  whole  nature  of  the  object. 
But  what  is  seen  is  real  in  so  far  forth  under  the  circumstances,  no 
matter  whether  it  would  be  unreal  under  other  circumstances.2 

There  is  a  certain  sense  in  which  men  stand  in  the  egocentric 
predicament,  viz.,  that  they  can  not  have  sensations  of  objects  with 
which  they  are  not  brought  in  contact  according  to  the  conditions 
of  object,  medium,  and  end-organ.  But  since  knowledge  is  not  a 
matter  of  sensations,  taken  singly  or  in  complexes,  there  is  no  ego- 
centric predicament  about  the  cognitive  experience.  Also  since  in 
sensation-processes  they  come  into  contact  with  the  natural,  the 
objective,  the  real  world,  there  is  no  egocentric  predicament  about 
the  metaphysical  status  of  sensations.  The  world  as  sensed  is  ipso 
facto  a  different  world  than  the  world  as  not  sensed,  just  as  the  end- 
organ  in  action  is  different  than  the  end-organ  not  in  action.  But 
it  is  important  to  determine  what  the  difference  is  from  an  examina- 
tion of  what  goes  on,  and  not  to  settle  such  questions  by  a  definition 
of  what  a  metaphysical  difference  might  be.  Certainly  as  we  observe 
the  facts,  there  is  no  problem  of  the  existence  of  an  external  world. 
There  may  well  be  problems  as  to  the  nature  and  the  qualities  of  the 
seen  objects  in  some  of  their  unseen  relationships  which  are  not 
directly  observed.  We  may  well  ask  such  questions  as  the  following : 

2  Lest  there  be  misunderstanding  as  to  the  meaning  of  real  in  the  above 
paragraph,  it  might  be  noted  that  the  term  refers  simply  to  what  is  "  there," 
i.e.,  to  what  exists  at  any  moment.  No  supposition  of  always  and  forever  en- 
during is  implied.  Becently  Mr.  C.  A.  Strong  wrote:  "If  we  say  that  data 
are  real,  we  are  forced  to  say  that  physical  things  are  not  real,  while,  if  we  say 
that  physical  things  are  real — as  I  think  we  must — we  are  forced  to  conclude 
that  data,  as  such,  are  not  real."  (Essays  in  Critical  Realism,  p.  225.)  But  the 
bewildering  dilemma  clears  up  when  Mr.  Strong  explains  at  the  end  of  his  para- 
graph, in  a  phrase  which  seems  to  have  been  added  at  the  last  moment  to  meet 
the  objections  of  one  of  hia  co-authors,  that  real  means  ' '  continuously  existent. ' ' 
Such  usage,  if  unusual,  has  ample  historical  precedent,  but  b  not  the  meaning 
of  the  word  in  this  paper. 


THE  METAPHYSICAL  STATUS  OF  SENSATIONS     173 

What  color  would  the  object  be  in  a  mist?  What  would  the  object 
look  like  under  a  microscope?  Could  we  see  the  object  through  a 
certain  intervening  substance  ?  Could  we  see  the  object  from  a  cer- 
tain distance  ?  What  is  the  chemical  constitution  of  the  object  ?  At 
what  rate  do  the  atoms  of  which  it  is  composed  vibrate  ?  Etc.  etc.  But 
we  could  not  legitimately  ask  whether  there  is  "really"  an  object 
there ;  for  it  is  given  as ' '  there. ' '  We  could  not  legitimately  ask  wheth- 
er it  is  "really"  white;  for  if  we  know  what  the  question  means,  we 
will  know  that  in  one  sense  it  is  white  and  in  another  sense  it  is  not, 
and  if  the  question  means  neither  of  these  things,  there  is  no  such 
thing  as  being  "really"  white.  We  never  have  the  task  of  getting 
from  the  realm  of  "psychic  states"  into  the  world  of  physical 
existences,  but  simply  the  task  of  getting  from  the  world  as  it  is 
partially  perceived  to  the  world  as  it  is  more  largely  inferred  to  be.3 
The  problem  of  knowledge  is  the  practical  one  of  how  to  go  from 
incomplete  information  to  more  complete  understanding.  That 
problem  can  not  be  said  to  involve  a  dualism,  in  any  of  the  ordinary 
or  historic  senses  of  that  word;  it  involves  only  a  dualism  between 
the  less  and  the  more,  both  of  which  are  contained  in  the  same  total 
system  of  reality.  We  do  not  infer  what  things  are  like  on  the  basis 
of  "psychic  states"  or  "ideas  wholly  in  the  mind";  but  we  infer 
what  things  are  like  in  their  entirety  from  those  of  their  qualities 
and  relations  which  we  do  directly  perceive.  Objects  do  not  cease 
to  be  objects  in  becoming  seen  any  more  than  they  cease  to  be  objects 
in  becoming  eaten.  That,  I  take  it,  is  what  Plato  meant  when  he  said 
that  the  object  "becomes  not  whiteness  but  white."  At  least,  whether 
Plato  meant  that  or  not,  it  can  be  said  that  in  vision  objects  do  not 
themselves  become,  and  do  not  produce  as  a  sort  of  by-product,  what 
are  usually  called  "psychic  states,"  but  become  seen  objects.  And 
sensation  presents  us  with  no  difficulty  except  that  of  discovering 
from  incomplete  presentation  of  the  world  we  confront  certain  other 

s  Two  statements  in  the  recent  Essays  in  Critical  Eealism  deserve  comment 
here.  Mr.  Strong  said:  "  The  world  as  sense-perception  presents  it  and  the 
world  as  it  is  by  no  means  coincide  "  (227).  In  one  sense  this  is  quite  true; 
for  the  object  seen  is  not  at  all  times  and  apart  from  perception  exactly  what 
it  is  seen  to  be  in  vision.  But  in  another  sense  the  statement  is  false;  for  the 
world  as  sense-perception  presents  it  is  a  part  of  the  world  as  it  is,  though  a 
small  part.  Mr.  A.  K.  Eogers  said  in  the  same  volume:  "  The  world  of  science 
is  distinctly  not  the  world  of  immediate  perception  "  (151).  This  is  true  of 
physics  and  astronomy  to  a  large  extent;  for  those  sciences  are  interested  in 
certain  aspects  of  the  world  not  presented  in  sensations.  But  it  is  not  true  of 
optics,  acoustics,  and  such  sciences.  And  it  is  entirely  false  if  it  is  meant 
that  there  is  any  metaphysical  difference  between  the  world  of  science  and  the 
world  of  immediate  perception. 


174  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

aa  yet  unobserved  and  perhaps  permanently  unobservable  items  in 
which  we  may  happen  to  be  interested.  Metaphysics  and  episte- 
mology  can  not  properly  be  concerned  with  an  alleged  hiatus  between 
two  different  sorts  of  existences,  but  with  the  distinction  between 
and  the  differences  in  the  things  as  seen  and  the  same  things  as  not 
seen,  all  of  which  exist  in  one  continuous  realm  of  being.  Men  come 
into  limited  contact  with  things  through  sensations  and  need  to 
know  lots  of  facts  about  their  world  which  can  only  be  discovered 
indirectly,  on  the  basis  of  analogy,  of  inference,  of  hypothesis  and 
experimentation.  In  other  words,  in  addition  to  the  knowledge  which 
may  be  directly  derived  from  such  sensations  as  those  of  vision,  we 
must  have  recourse  to  such  welkguided  reasonings  as  are  furnished 
to  us  by  such  sciences  as  optics,  physics,  and  chemistry. 

II 

The  view  of  sensations  thus  outlined,  whether  or  not  it  is  to  be 
found  in  Plato,  is  a  realism  or  naturalism.  But  it  differs  from, 
though  it  has  certain  sympathies  with,  two  commonly  accepted  the- 
ories, by  contrast  with  which  its  significance  would  perhaps  be  more 
obvious.  The  first  of  these  is  behaviorism ;  the  second  is  a  dualistic 
realism  represented  by  the  modern  tradition  which  comes  from  Locke 
and  Kant,  and  which  has  recently  been  restated,  in  an  effort  to  mini- 
mize the  dualism,  by  the  "critical  realists."  Though  no  effort  will 
here  be  made  to  review  those  alternative  views  of  sensation  in  any 
detail,  the  contrasts  may  be  helpful.4 

The  position  defended  in  this  paper  is  in  one  sense  of  the  word 
itself  a  behaviorism.  We  do  not  get  sensations  by  passively  waiting 
like  the  wax  for  the  imprint  of  the  seal.  We  would  not  call  the 
images  in  a  mirror  sensations  (that  is,  the  sensations  posseased  by 
the  mirror).  An  eye,  however  complete  in  all  its  parts,  would  prob- 
ably not  see  objects,  if  it  were  detached  from  the  organism  of  which 
it  is  an  integral  part.  Unless  there  is  reaction  by  as  well  as  action 
upon  the  eye,  vision  does  not  occur.  In  other  words,  the  eye  must 
be  the  end-organ  of  some  physiological  unit  of  response,  since  it  is 
probably  safe  to  affirm  that  the  eye  taken  by  itself  could  not  respond 
at  all.  Sensations,  as  the  term  has  been  used  in  this  paper,  are  cer- 
tain qualities  such  as  blue  and  red,  sweet  and  sour,  hot  and  cold; 
but  these  qualities  appear  only  in  connection  with  a  certain  process 

«  A  paper  to  follow  this  paper  will  examine  the  claim  of  the  * '  critical 
realists  "  to  have  overcome  the  difficulties  of  the  traditional  epistemological 
dualism  through  their  new  doctrine  of  the  datum  as  a  logical  essence.  But  for 
any  such  examination,  a  preliminary  constructive  statement  seemed  advisable 
of  the  point  of  view  from  which  criticism  would  be  brought. 


THE  METAPHYSICAL  STATUS  OF  SENSATIONS     175 

which  involves  object,  medium,  and  end-organ,  and  the  activity  of 
all  those  elements  is  jointly  necessary.  None  of  the  qualities  which 
are  revealed  by  the  process  can  be  taken  to  invalidate  the  process, 
to  throw  doubt  upon  the  reality  of  the  fact  that  there  has  been  such 
a  process,  to  deny  the  reality  of  the  conditions  under  which  the  proc- 
ess takes  place.  The  description  of  the  sensation-processes  from  the 
standpoint  of  the  organism  is  what  behaviorism  has  to  tell  us  about 
sensation,  and  is  accepted  as  valid  and  convincing  by  the  writer  of 
this  paper. 

None  the  less  the  standpoint  of  this  paper  is  opposed  to  much 
contemporary  behaviorism.  The  chief  reason  why  behaviorism  has 
not  been  even  more  widely  and  unanimously  adopted  in  America 
than  has  been  the  case,  and  why  the  present  writer  finds  it  partly 
unacceptable,  is  that  behaviorists  have  often  denied  the  reality 
of  obvious  facts  in  the  interests  of  the  simplicity  of  their  theories. 
When  behaviorism  arose  shortly  after  1890,  largely  as  the  result  of 
the  impetus  given  to  psychological  studies  by  William  James,  many 
philosophers  were  found  describing  the  mind  as  a  mere  series  of 
the  sense-qualities  which  the  processes  of  sensation  bring  into  exis- 
tence. It  was  quite  natural  therefore  that  a  reaction  from  this  in- 
complete description  should  take  place,  and  that  not  simply  the  mind 
should  be  described  in  terms  of  the  processes  of  sensation  and  the 
like,  but  the  very  existence  of  the  sense-qualities  should  be  neglected 
and  in  more  extreme  cases  denied.5  At  least,  whether  natural  or  not, 
such  did  take  place.  Preoccupied  with  an  analysis  of  the  actions 
of  the  nervous  system,  behaviorists  had  nothing  to  say  about  the 
qualities  which  the  objects  have  in  sensation.  Called  to  account  for 
this  neglect,  they  feared  that  they  were  being  summoned  once  more 
to  study  merely  these  qualities;  and  knowing  to  their  own  satisfac- 
tion that  what  they  had  discovered  about  the  mind  could  never  be 
stated  in  any  mere  list  of  such  qualities,  however  complete,  they 
asserted  that  the  mind  was  activity,  not  quality  at  all.  Furthermore, 
fearing  a  renewal  of  the  epistemological  futilities  of  which  modern 
philosophy  has  given  such  frequent  instances,  they  were  prompted 
to  deny  the  existence  of  ' '  psychic  states ' ' ;  and  since  their  adversaries 
assured  them  that  the  qualities  revealed  in  sensation  were  "psychic 
states, ' '  they  denied  the  very  existence  of  the  qualities  altogether. 

8  Mr.  J.  B.  Watson  only  harms  his  own  cause  by  his  impossible  identifica- 
tion of  colors  or  other  qualities  of  an  object  with  a  physiological  process.  E.g., 
he  recently  quoted  Dunlap  with  approval  to  the  effect  that  "  the  so-called 
visual  image  is  only  an  associated  eye  muscle  strain  (muscular  '  sensation  ')." 
Cf.  The  Dial,  Vol.  LXXII.,  No.  1,  p.  101,  Jan.,  1922.  This  is  only  a  new  form 
of  the  traditional  materialistic  fallacy. 


176  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

To  a  certain  extent  the  dispute  has  been  merely  verbal.  If  any 
one  chooses  to  call  the  sense-qualities  which  appear  in  the  course 
of  the  sensation-processes  by  the  name  of  mind,  there  should  be 
no  objection — though  care  would  have  to  be  exercised  to  keep  from 
various  of  the  traditional  errors  which  have  accompanied  that  termin- 
ological practise  during  the  last  three  centuries.  Similarly  if  any 
one  chooses  to  call  the  activities  of  the  organism  in  sensation  and  the 
like  by  the  name  of  mind,  again  there  should  be  no  objection. 
Though  we  can  discover  no  reason  why  certain  qualities  should 
appear  exclusively  in  connection  with  certain  processes,  yet  such 
seems  to  be  the  fact.  If  either  thing  were  singled  out  as  that  in 
terms  of  which  alone  mind  is  to  be  defined,  the  behaviorist  has  cli 
the  better  element.  For  the  sense-quality  is  the  quality  of  the  object : 
it  is  neither  within  the  body  nor  within  the  confines  of  a  mental 
realm  distinguished  from  the  physical  world.  And  the  error  of  the 
behaviorist  is  decidedly  less  disastrous  than  that  of  the  upholders  of 
the  ' '  psychic  states ' ' ;  for  their  error  is  the  enthusiastic  one  of  youth 
in  overstating  a  new  discovery,  and  involves  no  distortion  of  reality 
in  so  far  as  their  positive,  if  not  their  negative,  arguments  are  con- 
cerned. 

Yet  the  issue  has  often  gone  further  than  a  verbal  dispute.  The 
behaviorists,  assured  from  their  own  studies  that  the  thing  they 
called  mind  was  a  certain  set  of  activities  of  the  physiological  organ- 
ism, and  assured  by  a  long  and  important  tradition  that  sense-quali- 
ties did  not  exist  outside  the  mind,  had  to  deny  that  there  were  any 
sense-qualities  at  all.  Mind  for  them  was  not  a  receptacle:  it  was 
not  a  place  in  which  anything  could  be  located.  Of  course  their 
denial  of  sense-qualities  was  an  error.  But  the  trap  which  led  them 
into  the  error  was  their  acceptance  of  the  supposition  that  sense- 
qualities  are  "psychic  states."  If  they  erred,  it  was  due  to  their 
trusting  the  word  of  those  philosophers  who,  in  Humian  fashion, 
treated  the  mind  as  a  series  of  states  of  consciousness  and  denied  the 
objectivity  of  sense-qualities.  They  are  not  to  be  much  reproached 
for  their  error;  for  the  premise  which  they  furnished  from  their 
own  experimental  work  was  true,  whereas  that  supplied  by  their 
fellow-philosophers,  if  true  at  all,  was  true  only  in  a  limited  and 
unusual  sense  of  the  words.  Those  who  are  worried  over  the  material- 
istic tendency  of  behaviorism  have  only  themselves  to  blame;  the 
error  of  behaviorism  can  be  corrected  only  upon  the  supposition 
of  the  objectivity  of  sense-qualities. 

The  time  has  come  to  locate  the  error  of  behaviorism  more  fairly. 
The  denial  of  the  existence  of  facts  which  every  man  perceives 
every  day  of  his  life  is  preposterous.  The  existence  of  sense-qualities 


THE  METAPHYSICAL  STATUS  OF  SENSATIONS     177 

does  not  have  to  be  proved,  because  it  is  given  as  an  immediate  fact 
of  experience.  Similarly  the  existence  of  the  activities  of  the  nervous 
system  does  not  need  to  be  proved  any  further  than  behaviorists 
have  done.  "What  we  need  is  to  learn  what  various  people  mean  by 
terms  such  as  mind,  and  then  state  the  well-proved  conclusions 
in  terms  the  meaning  of  which  may  be  clear  to  all.  No  one  probably 
would  question  that  object,  medium,  and  end-organ  are  all  essential 
to  that  sort  of  activity  of  the  physiological  organism  which  we  may 
then  agree  to  call  the  process  of  sensation.  Since  mind  is  usually 
contrasted  with  object,  we  would  do  better  not  to  call  by  the  name 
of  mind  the  sense-quality  which  the  object  assumes  during  and 
as  a  result  of  the  process  of  sensation;  for  the  sense-quality  is  a 
quality  of  the  object.  Avoiding  thus  the  term  mind  for  the  mere 
existence  of  sense-qualities,  we  should  recognize  none  the  less  their 
existence.  That  sense-qualities  are  perceived  and  living  processes 
are  carried  on  by  the  same  organisms  should  not  blind  us  to  both 
sets  of  facts.  The  behaviorists  have  neglected  or  even  denied  the 
former;  their  opponents  have  neglected  and  nearly  always  denied 
the  latter,  and  then  have  drawn  impossible  conclusions  from  what 
they  have  mistakenly  denied  as  well  as  from  what  they  have  truly 
affirmed.  It  is  theoretically  possible  that  some  other  cause  than 
the  sensation-process  might  give  rise  to  sense-qualities,  in  which 
case  no  one  surely  would  wish  to  speak  of  a  mind  as  present.  But 
it  is  actually  the  case  that  there  are  a  number  of  biological  and 
physiological  processes  which  seem  to  go  on  without  any  sensations, 
any  consciousness,  any  prevision  of  the  future;  and  yet  even  in 
these  processes  we  feel  that  we  have  something  akin  to  what  we 
mean  by  mind.  Thus,  though  it  is  not  the  purpose  of  this  paper 
to  define  mind,  it  can  at  least  be  said  that  the  term  seems  to  be 
best  used  for  those  of  the  living  processes  which  have  assumed  a 
certain  quality  and  a  certain  form.6 

e  A  word  of  warning  to  the  critics  of  a  revised  behaviorism  may  be  timely 
here.  Those  who  treat  the  mind  as  a  matter  of  activity  or  relationships  are 
usually  called  materialists.  But  that  characterization  is  not  always  correct.  It 
would  be  correct  if  the  relations  were  altogether  spatial,  if  the  activity  were 
that  of  gross  motion  such  as  waving  arms  and  legs  about  in  space.  But  usually 
the  relationships  and  activity  referred  to  are  ideal,  they  can  be  described  only 
in  terms  of  meaning,  anticipation  of  the  future,  inference,  judgment.  Mr. 
Sellars  remarked  that  knowledge  is  not  "  a  real  relation  between  the  knower  and 
the  known."  (Essays  in  Critical  Realism,  p.  206.)  I  have  not  been  able  to 
puzzle  out  what  he  is  intending  to  say.  But  his  words  would  seem  to  mean 
either  that  knowledge  did  not  exist  or  that  the  only  real  relations  were  spatial 
and  material.  I  do  not  wish  to  be  unfair.  Yet  I  can  not  help  but  think  that 
he  tends  to  equate  reality  and  matter,  and  to  be  by  implication  more  material- 
istic than  many  behaviorists. 


178  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

III 

The  opponents  of  behaviorism  have  almost  unanimously  treated 
sensations  as  "psychic  states"  existing  in  the  mind  and  having  no 
objective  status.  In  fact  this  treatment  has  become  so  customary 
that  it  is  often  taken  as  an  incontrovertible  axiom  which  needs  no 
proof.  Each  consciousness  is  then  cut  off  from  the  rest  of  the  world 
by  an  absolute  break.  And  the  world  of  nature,  the  objective  world, 
is  not  known  directly.7 

The  proofs  for  the  subjectivity  of  sensations  are  mostly  indirect, 
i.e.,  they  consist  in  showing  that  sensations  could  not  be  objective. 
There  are  three  such  proofs  which  have  frequently  been  offered  from 
Locke  to  the  "critical  realists,"  and  there  is  an  implicit  principle 
or  metaphysical  axiom  usually  assumed.  These  must  be  reviewed 
before  the  thesis  of  this  paper  can  be  taken  as  acceptable. 

The  arguments  can  be  briefly  summed  up:  (1)  that  different 
people  looking  at  the  same  object  have  different  sensations,  and  the 
sensations  are  therefore  not  really  in  the  object  but  only  imagina- 
tively projected  there;  (2)  that  objects  seem  to  have  contradictory 
qualities  and  hence  the  qualities  must  be,  not  in  the  object,  but  in 
the  mind;  (3)  that  the  qualities  we  discover  are  different  from  what 
we  know  on  other  grounds  to  be  the  nature  of  the  objects  and  hence 
can  not  be  in  the  objects  at  all.8  Now  all  these  arguments  are 
good  as  a  refutation  of  "naive  realism"  which  supposes  objects  to 
be  at  all  times  just  what  they  are  seen  at  any  one  moment  to  be — 
though  it  may  be  doubted  if  the  most  naive  man-in-the-street  ever 
held  such  a  position.  But  none  of  them  militates  against  the  argu- 
ment for  the  objectivity  of  sensations  as  set  forth  in  this  paper. 
(1)  Different  people  looking  at  the  same  object  of  course  have  dif- 
ferent sensations,  which  proves  that  the  sense-quality  is  not  in  the 
object  taken  alone  and  absolutely,  but  which  does  not  prove  that 
the  object  may  not  have  the  various  different  qualities  relatively 
to  the  different  situations  in  which  it  stands  to  different  organisms. 
Relativity  is  not  subjectivity;  and  in  these  days  of  relativity,  when 
even  physicists  talk  in  such  terms,  the  old  thoughtless  identification 
of  the  relative  and  the  subjective  requires  revision.  If  sensations 
are  relative  to  medium  and  end-organ  as  well  as  to  object,  the  con- 

7  E.g.,  in  Essays  in  Critical  Eed'ism,  it  is  said  that  psychology  deals  with 
"  subjective  data  "  (31),  that  the  sphere  of  the  psychologist  is  "  the  psychical 
aa  such  "  (208),  that  a  sensation,  apart  from  its  reference,  is  but  "  a  pure 
state  of  our  sensibility  "  (234),  that  "  perception  is  not  direct  "  (103),  etc. 
Cf.  also  pp.  11,  28,  164,  192,  197,  217,  et  passim. 

•  For  the  most  recent  statement  of  these  arguments  in  compact  form,  con- 
sult Essays  in  Critical  Eealism,  pp.  8,  15,  133,  224,  226,  etc. 


THE  METAPHYSICAL  STATUS  OF  SENSATIONS     179 

ditions  of  observation  would  assist  in  determining  what  quality 
would  be  seen.  Under  identically  the  same  circumstances  the  object 
has  identically  the  same  quality.  (2)  The  contradictory  qualities, 
being  also  a  matter  of  diverse  points  of  view,  signify  nothing  in 
the  way  of  subjectivity.  For  the  contradictory  qualities  are  not 
in  the  object  taken  alone.  The  trouble  here  seems  to  arise  from 
considering  qualities  as  distinct  and  separate  entities,  like  a  lot 
of  marbles  which  small  boys  carry  around  in  their  pockets.  The 
sense-qualities  of  objects  are  relative  to  the  point  of  view.  And 
unless  it  is  contradictory  to  suppose  that  there  is  more  than  one 
point  of  view  in  the  universe,  it  is  hard  to  see  why  it  is  contradic- 
tory to  suppose  an  object  to  have  successively  to  the  same  organism 
or  simultaneously  to  different  organisms  a  number  of  different  quali- 
ties. (3)  The  fact  referred  to  in  the  third  argument  is  not  a 
point  against  the  theory  of  this  paper,  but  part  of  the  position 
defended.  But  the  inference  from  that  fact  betrays  a  non  sequitur. 
Because  an  object  does  not  have  eternally  and  unchangeably  a  cer- 
tain quality  observed  in  sensation,  is  no  reason  why  it  may  not  have 
that  quality  in  case  of  being  related  in  a  certain  way  to  a  certain 
perceiving  organism.  It  is  a  long  jump  from  the  discovery  that 
the  qualities  observed  in  sensation  are  not  the  qualities  which  the 
object  has  apart  from  sensation,  to  the  conclusion  that  the  qualities 
are  not  qualities  of  the  object  at  all  but  "psychic  states"  in  the 
mind.  Before  such  a  conclusion  could  be  defended,  one  would  have 
to  find  such  a  "mind"  as  could  contain  qualities,  which  kind  of  a 
"mind"  is  not  revealed  by  experience;  and  even  then,  one  would 
need  some  experimental  evidence  for  the  location  of  qualities  there 
instead  of  somewhere  else.  No  one  has  ever  successfully  essayed 
this  task.  Rather  such  a  supposition  is  defined  as  an  axiom  and 
accepted  as  authentic  before  experience  is  examined,  and  experience 
is  then  made  to  fit  into  this  scheme  at  any  cost. 

In  addition  to  these  arguments  which  are  restated  in  various 
forms,  there  is  an  alleged  metaphysical  principle  which  is  supposed 
to  prove  the  subjectivity  of  sensations.  Instead  of  going  to  expe- 
rience to  find  out  whether  we  can  really  see  and  touch  objects,  the 
advocates  of  subjectivism  adduce  an  a  priori  proof  against  such 
direct  contact  between  observer  and  object.9  Mind  and  matter  are 
so  regarded  that  contact  between  them  is  deemed  impossible. 

9  E.g.,  Mr.  E.  W.  Sellars  said  that  the  claim  to  have  the  object  immediately 
present  is  "  impossible,"  and  his  reason  is  that  "  it  would  involve  the  leaping 
of  spatial  and  temporal  barriers  in  an  unnatural  fashion  "  (Essays  in  Critical 
Eealism,  p.  200).  The  quite  sufficient  answer  to  Mr.  Sellars  and  all  the  other 
critical  realists  who  reject  the  contact  of  observer  with  object  is  contained  in 
the  wise  words  of  Mr.  Santayana  in  their  own  volume:  "  The  standard  of 
naturalness  is  nature  itself  "  (p.  167). 


180  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

The  trouble  here  seems  to  be  with  the  conception  of  cause.  The 
assumption  seems  to  have  been  made  that  one  thing  can  not  cause 
another  thing  unless  we  can  mulct-stand  how  the  act  of  causation 
takes  place.  But  causation,  however  natural  a  matter,  is  not  a 
logical  procedure.  A  person  who  looked  at  the  greenish-yellow 
gas  called  chlorin  with  its  disagreeable  odor  and  poisonous  effect 
upon  the  lungs  and  then  looked  at  the  whitish  metal  called  sodium 
which  discolors  so  quickly  as  it  oxidizes  when  exposed  to  the  air, 
might  never  suspect  that  those  two  substances,  combined  in  certain 
proportions,  would  give  another  substance  indispensable  to  living 
organisms  and  delicious  for  the  seasoning  of  food.  We  can  dis- 
cover certain  facts  which  we  can  not  account  for;  yet  metaphysics 
should  not  be  regarded  as  a  process  of  accounting  for  the  universe 
but  as  a  statement  in  general  terms  of  what  the  universe  happens 
to  be.  Similarly  we  may  be  unable  to  explain  why  certain  kinds  of 
matter,  organized  in  a  certain  way,  make  living  beings  and  end- 
organs  and  nervous  systems;  and  we  may  be  unable  to  explain 
why  under  certain  circumstances  these  living  beings  can  perceive  ob- 
jects. We  are  entitled  to  seek  explanation  of  these  facts  in  the  sense 
that  we  may  search  for  the  detailed  analysis  of  the  processes  involved, 
but  not  in  the  sense  that  we  may  formulate  a  principle  which  will 
account  for  things  being  as  they  are  instead  of  otherwise.  However 
unrelated  to  logical  processes  they  may  be,  natural  processes  are 
none  the  less  real,  i.e.,  take  place ;  they  do  not  wait  for  the  logician 
to  justify  their  occurrence.  Causation  is  not  anything  to  be  ex- 
plained en  masse,  but  to  be  accepted  and  to  be  used  as  an  explanation 
of  what  happens  to  and  around  us.  Nature  is  more  resourceful 
than  the  mind  of  a  rationalist.  Antecedent  intelligibility  is  not  a 
measure  of  natural  possibility.  What  is,  is  possible.  If  we  do 
perceive  objects,  then  we  can.  Metaphysicians  should  start  with  na- 
ture, not  with  axioms ;  and  their  principles  should  be  generalizations 
from  the  facts,  not  regulations  by  which  they,  like  traffic  police- 
men for  the  universe,  endeavor  to  determine  the  directions  in  which 
things  must  go. 

Doubtless  many  advocates  of  the  existence  of  "psychic  states" 
would  reject  the  false  metaphysical  axiom  discussed  in  the  preced- 
ing paragraph.  But  if  they  carry  out  that  rejection  and  eliminate 
its  implications  from  all  their  theories,  what  antecedent  likelihood 
is  there  that  objects  have  not  "really"  the  qualities  which  they 
are  found  in  experience  to  have,  and  that  we  do  not,  in  spite  of 
every  indication,  "really"  come  into  immediate  contact  with  ob- 
jects? Thus  the  way  is  opened  for  a  return  to  a  naturalism  which 
takes  the  universe  at  face-value,  gives  credit  to  whatever  it  finds 


TRUTH  AS  CORRESPONDENCE  181 

and  seeks  for  as  much  more  as  it  can  discover,  and  recognizes  the 
setting  in  which  living,  perceiving,  and  thinking  go  on.  Naturalism 
in  this  sense  is  far  from  materialism ; 10  for  it  regards  the  material 
world  as  the  "natural  basis"  which  finds  its  "ideal  fulfilment"  in 
the  achievement  of  the  goods  which  the  structure  of  reality  makes 
possible.11  And  thus  from  the  slime  of  the  sea-bed  may  arise  beings 
who  sing  songs,  build  cathedrals,  erect  shrines  to  the  saints,  and 
dream  of  the  kingdom  of  God.  But  the  full  meaning  of  naturalism 
is  too  much  to  attempt  to  define  in  a  closing  paragraph.  It  is  per- 
haps enough  if  something  has  been  said  to  reinforce  Plato's  con- 
tention that  in  vision  the  eye  becomes  a  seeing  eye,  and  the  object 
becomes  a  white  object. 

STERLING  P.  LAMPRECHT. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  ILLINOIS. 


TRUTH  AS  CORRESPONDENCE :  A  RE-DEFINITION 

FTlHE  purpose  of  this  article  is. to  show  that  by  an  accurate  ob- 
-L  jective  definition  of  the  concepts  involved  it  is  possible  to 
define  truth  in  terms  of  correspondence,  and  at  the  same  time  avoid 
the  well-known  dialectical  difficulties  of  the  theory  of  error.  Many 
attempts  along  this  line  have  been  made,  but  they  have  proved 
abortive.  The  advocates  of  what  Joachim  calls  the  coherence  theory 
have  found  them  altogether  too  easy  to  puncture.  Granting  that 
a  true  statement  is  one  that  corresponds  with  facts,  they  say,  how 
are  we  to  deal  with  false  statements'?  We  can  not  claim  that  they 
correspond  to  nothing  at  all,  for  this  would  imply  that  they  were 
meaningless,  which  is  not  the  case.  And  we  can  not  say  that  they 
correspond  with  the  wrong  facts,  for  how  can  we  determine  their 
legitimate  reference?  In  spite  of  the  seeming  finality  of  such  ob- 
jections, the  correspondence  theory  of  truth  still  survives.  And 
it  survives  because  of  its  obvious  scientific  common  sense.  But  to 
a  really  striking  degree  epistemology  has  failed  to  put  it  on  a 
sound  logical  basis.  Propositions,  assumptions,  and  other  strange 
and  doubtful  entities  have  been  invented  to  mediate  between  judg- 
ment and  reality,  and  they  are  all  conspicuously  futile. 

The  correct  solution  is  not  by  means  of  any  of  these  ingenuities. 
It  is  found  by  taking  an  objective  point  of  view  in  regard  to  the 
knowledge  situation,  and  the  factors  entering  into  it.  Our  funda- 

10  The  word  naturalism  has  not  in  this  paper  at  all  the  same  meaning  as, 
for  example,  in  Professor  Perry's  Present  Philosophical  Tendencies. 

11  These  phrases  are  borrowed  from  Santayana's  Life  of  Reason. 


182  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

mental  a&sumption  is  that  knowledge  is  a  function  of  reality.  And 
our  problem  is  so  to  define  this  relationship  as  to  avoid  the  diffi- 
culties so  often  pointed  cut  in  connection  with  other  correspond- 
ence theories  of  truth. 

To  begin  with  a  study  of  the  terms  of  the  relation,  what  are  we 
to  understand  by  knowledge!  Objectively  considered,  we  may  take 
knowledge  to  consist  of  speech-reactions.  That  is  to  say,  it  is  a 
particular  type  of  behavior.  At  first  sight  this  may  appear  very 
paradoxical,  but  only  because  philosophy  has  paid  little  attention  to 
the  point.  For  it  is  by  no  means  repugnant  to  the  common  sense 
of  man.  Humanity  has  inevitably  perceived  the  necessity  of  in- 
venting adequate  means  for  keeping  permanent  records  of  speech- 
reactions.  A  page  of  writing  is  just  as  much  a  record  of  reactions 
as  is  the  tracery  on  the  smoked  cylinder  by  which  the  subject  of  a 
psychological  experiment  shows  his  responses  to  the  flashing  of 
lights,  the  tones  of  bells  or  other  stimuli.  But  the  writing  is  an 
exceedingly  complex  and  ingenious  record  of  highly  complex  re- 
sponses, whereas  the  tracery  on  the  smoked  surface  is  a  relatively 
simple,  two-dimensional  affair.  Thus  the  type  of  behavior  known 
as  language  has  evidently  been  given  very  great  weight  by  the 
common  consent  of  man,  and  the  difficulty  of  regarding  knowledge 
as  language  is  sensibly  diminished. 

There  are,  however,  two  objections,  one  systematic,  the  other 
psychological,  that  must  be  met  before  we  can  proceed.  In  the 
first  place  it  may  be  said  that  we  are  defining  knowledge  in  terms 
of  something  that  is  not  knowledge,  and  that  this  involves  a  re- 
flexive fallacy.  For  if  we  say  that  all  knowledge  is  speech,  it  may 
seem  that  we  are  making  one  of  those  assertions  about  all  proposi- 
tions that  are  forbidden  by  the  Theory  of  Types.  But  this  is  not 
a  case  of  defining  one  entity  in  terms  of  another.  We  do  not  have 
knowledge  on  the  one  hand  and  speech  on  the  other.  From  the 
objective  point  of  view  we  have  nothing  but  speech.  The  whole 
material  of  logic  itself  is  nothing  but  speech-reactions. 

But,  in  the  second  place,  it  may  be  said  that  we  are  arguing  far 
in  advance  of  the  known  facts.  It  is  by  no  manner  of  means 
established  that  all  cognitive  processes  are  essentially  language- 
processes.  This  is  true  enough,  but  there  is  no  lack  of  negative 
evidence  in  support  of  our  contention.  Within  recent  years  ex- 
tensive attempts  have  been  made  both  in  this  country  and  in  Europe 
to  demonstrate  the  existence  of  so-called  imageless  thought.  The 
fate  of  this  research  is  quite  instructive.  In  laboratories  of  marked 
sensationalist  tendency,  imageless  thought  was  never  discovered, 
while  in  laboratories  of  an  anti-sensationalist  turn,  it  was.  Such 


TRUTH  AS  CORRESPONDENCE  183 

an  outcome  can  hardly  fail  to  cast  serious  reflections  on  the  whole 
method  of  introspective  psychology.  And  specifically,  it  is  relev- 
ant to  our  present  discussion  in  that  it  suggests  the  impossibility 
of  dealing  with  cognition  in  terms  of  impressions.  Knowledge 
would  seem  to  be  an  affair  of  reactions.  And  the  only  kind  of 
behavior  that  can  well  be  regarded  as  knowledge  is  speech.  Of 
course  when  we  come  to  the  positive  side  of  the  question,  and  try 
to  show  that  in  every  case  of  cognition  a  speech  reaction  is  present, 
the  difficulties  are  immense.  Oftentimes  the  responses  will  be  ex- 
ceedingly subtle.  There  will  be  no  evident  motions  of  the  vocal 
organs  or  the  hands.  There  will  perhaps  be  not  even  any  palpable 
muscular  innervations.  The  only  changes  may  be  in  the  cortex, 
where  we  have  at  present  no  means  of  observing  them.  But  the 
decided  weight  of  argument  seems  to  be  on  the  side  of  the  supposi- 
tion that  from  the  objective  point  of  view,  cognition  appears  as 
language. 

But  must  we  not  admit  that  types  of  behavior  other  than  speech 
are  cognitive  in  function — such  for  instance  as  pointing  or  draw- 
ing geometrical  figures?  When  I  reply  to  the  question,  "Where 
is  the  book?"  by  pointing,  is  this  response  not  essentially  knowl- 
edge from  the  objective  point  of  view?  Hardly,  for  it  would  seem 
very  much  more  in  accord  with  the  probable  psychological  facts 
to  suppose  that  the  cognitive  part  of  the  proceeding  would  be 
found  in  some  such  suppressed,  implicit  speech-reaction  as:  "The 
book  is  where  I  am  pointing."  Again,  it  has  been  proposed  that 
we  try  to  communicate  with  hypothetical  rational  inhabitants  of 
Mars  by  means  of  a  figure  of  the  Theorem  of  Pythagoras  done 
large  in  canals  on  the  Sahara  desert.  Would  not  the  behaviors 
involved  in  planning  and  executing  such  a  figure  be  essentially 
cognitive?  Not  so,  for  the  essential  meaning,  the  knowledge  con- 
veyed by  such  a  figure,  both  to  ourselves  and  to  the  Martians, 
would  consist  in  the  speech-reactions  of  which  it  would  be  the 
stimulus. 

An  apparently  serious  difficulty  in  regarding  knowledge  as 
consisting  of  speech  reactions  is  found  in  the  phenomena  of  quali- 
tative perception.  When  I  look  at  a  red  object,  and  see  before 
me  a  patch  of  red,  there  seems  to  be  something  very  direct  and 
immediate  in  the  situation.  I  seem  to  have  what  Bertrand  Rus- 
sell calls  "knowledge  by  acquaintance."  In  such  respects  it  ap- 
pears, prima  facie,  that  cognition  is  a  matter  of  impression  rather 
than  reaction.  But  what  actually  happens?  An  ethereal  vibration 
of  a  certain  frequency  impinges  upon  the  retina,  and  presumably, 
a  certain  kind  of  stimulus  travels  up  over  the  optic  nerve.  Does 


184  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

this  constitute  knowledge?  It  is  difficult  to  say  that  it  does.  So 
far,  it  would  appear,  we  have  nothing  at  all  but  various  metabolic 
changes.  Of  course  the  inner  secret  soul  or  consciousness  of  the 
subject  may  register  something.  But  the  outside  observer  knows 
nothing  of  all  this.  Still  less  does  he  know  that  the  impression  is 
one  of  redness.  Indeed  the  very  members  of  the  subject  himself 
are  not  aware  of  it  at  this  stage.  If  we  insist  on  stopping  here, 
the  whole  business  becomes  a  little  secret  between  his  cortex  and 
his  soul.  Indeed,  it  is  only  when  the  stimulus  goes  across  into 
response  that  it  becomes  anything  at  all.  If  the  subject  is  a  bull, 
and  charges,  we  say  that  he  is  infuriated.  If  he  is  a  man,  and  says 
"That  is  red"  we  say  that  he  has  knowledge.  Even  in  the  experi- 
mental psychology  of  sensation,  where  we  might  expect  to  find 
pure  impressions  if  they  exist  anywhere,  all  the  data  are  in  the 
form  of  speech-reactions,  the  reports  of  the  subjects. 

Knowledge  then,  as  a  set  of  propositions  or  judgments,  is  some- 
thing that  possesses  physical  reality.  It  has  a  position  in  space 
and  a  duration  in  time.  Certainly  the  mere  geometrical  relations 
of  a  piece  of  knowledge,  a  speech-reaction,  are  not  of  the  first  im- 
portance. Its  structural  correlations  with  the  responding  organism 
are  the  truly  significant  considerations.  It  is  these  which  science 
must  analyze.  But  to  point  out  that  a  judgment  has  the  same  kind 
of  ponderable  reality  as  a  chair  is  far  from  being  a  waste  of  time. 
It  instantly  banishes  many  of  those  vague  and  mystifying  difficul- 
ties which  have  led  epistemology  into  endless  and  futile  dialectical 
mazes,  and  goes  far  towards  clearing  up  the  whole  discussion  as  to 
the  nature  of  truth. 

This  brings  to  our  attention  the  second  element  in  the  cognitive 
situation,  the  object  of  knowledge.  And  here  it  would  seem  that 
we  must  inevitably  take  up  the  position  which  Bosanquet  and  the 
idealists  have  called  "naive  realism."  The  object  of  knowledge  will 
be  the  thing  of  physics,  the  thing,  that  is  to  say,  which  by  possess- 
ing mass,  momentum  and  so  forth  satisfies  the  requirements  of, 
and  is  intelligible  to  physical  science. 

Bertrand  Russell  has  several  times  discussed  the  relation  of  the 
things  of  physics  to  consciousness.  In  general,  ignoring  minor 
differences,  his  theory  is  that  physical  objects  may  be  regarded  as 
aggregations  of  sense-data.  In  this  respect,  of  course,  he  is  simply 
making  a  refinement  upon  the  position  of  Hume.  It  is  notable 
that  this  point  of  view  admittedly  culminates  in  solipsism,  which  of 
itself  would  be  enough  to  suggest  that  it  must  be  based  on  some 
radical  error.  For  philosophers  have  almost  always  felt  that  solip- 
sism is  in  the  nature  of  a  reductio  ad  absurdum,  even  when  they 
have  not  seen  their  way  clear  to  avoiding  it. 


TRUTH  AS  CORRESPONDENCE  185 

The  fundamental  objection  to  defining  physical  things  in  terms 
of  sense-data  is  that  the  existence  of  sense-data  themselves  is  very 
doubtful.  Of  course  it  is  allowed  that  sense-data  are  not  found  in 
a  pure  or  uncombined  condition,  which,  though  it  certainly  raises 
serious  difficulties,  may  not  be  fatal  to  Russell's  theory.  But  this 
is  by  no  means  all.  A  thoroughgoing  objective  psychology  denies 
that  the  patch  of  color  of  a  given  shape  and  size  which  is  a  constitu- 
ent of  the  aggregate  of  data  which  makes  up  the  thing  according 
to  Russell,  is  anything  at  all  in  and  of  itself.  Unless  the  stimulus 
issues  in  response,  unless  it  affects  the  behavior  of  the  organism 
in  some  definite  manner,  we  have  no  reason  to  believe  that  it  exists 
as  a  stimulus  at  all.  It  is  with  responses  that  we  are  always  con- 
cerned. Thus  it  is  impossible  to  admit  of  sense-data  as  ultimate 
notions  for  epistemology.  And  the  paradoxical  issue  of  the  at- 
tempt to  reconstruct  the  things  of  physics  as  groupings  of  sense- 
data,  the  fact  that  it  directly  involves  such  a  position  as  solipsism, 
is  due  to  employing  fictions  as  ultimates. 

It  would  be  very  much  better  to  regard  the  things  of  physics 
as  classes  of  reactions.  Indeed  it  might  be  suggested  that  this  was 
the  way  out  if  the  notion  of  sense-data  proved  untenable.  But 
this  would  at  once  wreck  the  geometrical  scheme  by  which  Russell 
constructs  the  world  of  physics  out  of  appearances.  If  we  admit 
sense-data  as  he  understands  them,  it  is  possible  to  suppose  a  rela- 
tion of  congruence  between  them.  And  in  terms  of  this,  and  one 
or  two  other  concepts,  such  as  larger  and  smaller,  and  shielding,  it 
is  not  difficult  to  derive  direction  and  line.  This  done,  we  define 
a  thing  as  the  class  of  all  lines  (which  themselves  are  classes  of 
sense-data)  which  converge  at  a  given  locus.  But  with  responses 
the  case  is  altogether  different.  It  is  out  of  the  question  to  set 
up  such  relations  and  to  derive  such  a  scheme  in  this  case.  There 
is  a  sense  in  which  the  thing  might  be  regarded  as  the  class  of  all 
responses  in  regard  to  it.  But  inasmuch  as  all  such  responses  are 
occasioned  by  stimuli,  we  can  never  escape  from  duality.  The 
conception  of  a  class  of  responses  may  conceivably  have  a  value, 
but  the  principle  of  Occam's  razor  can  never  get  rid  of  entities 
called  things,  which  are  the  causes  of  the  stimuli  issuing  in  these 
responses. 

Thus  it  would  seem  that  the  adoption  of  an  objective  point  of 
view  not  only  results  in  giving  up  knowledge  by  acquaintance,  but 
also  commits  us  to  a  naive  realism  in  regard  to  the  objects  of  knowl- 
edge. For  those  objects  appear  merely  as  the  things  of  physics. 
Beyond  this  point  analysis  can  not  be  pushed. 

But  it  will  be  said  that  this  completely  ignores  so-called  ab- 
stract knowledge,  which  purports  to  deal  not  with  ponderable  in- 


186  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

dividual  things,  but  with  universals.  Univereals,  however,  can 
always  be  regarded  as  classes  of  things.  And  Russell's  theory  of 
incomplete  symbols  shows  that  the  class  concepts  are  nothing  but 
symbolic  conveniences.  In  other  words,  we  deal  with  universals 
by  means  of  nominalism.  Millenniums  of  adjustment  have  so  re- 
fined human  speech-reactions,  that  it  is  possible  for  us  to  use  the 
convenience  known  as  abstract  thought. 

The  result  of  our  discussion  so  far  is  that  in  the  cognitive 
situation  we  have  a  relation  set  up  between  two  classes  of  physical 
objects.  On  the  one  hand  we  have  the  specific  object  known  as  a 
speech-reaction;  on  the  other,  anything  else,  to  which  the  speech- 
reaction  somehow  refers.  Philosophy  has  usually  dealt  with  the 
cognitive  situation  by  revising  its  conception  of  the  object  of 
knowledge.  The  tendency  has  been  towards  a  monism  in  favor  of 
knowledge  as  something  at  any  rate  non-physical.  The  idealist 
has  tried  to  show  that  the  understanding  makes  nature.  The 
empiricist  has  tried  to  show  that  nature  may  be  regarded  as  made 
up  of  sense  impressions.  Common  to  both  is  the  attempt  to  show 
that  nature  participates  in  the  very  essence  of  consciousness.  Our 
own  position  here  is  the  precise  converse  of  this.  It  is  a  monism 
in  favor  of  physical  reality.  It  claims  that  knowledge  itself  is 
part  of  nature,  that  it  is  a  specific  phenomenon  among  phenomena. 
When  we  regard  knowledge  as  a  set  of  speech-reactions,  the  mysteri- 
ous gap  between  mind  and  matter  is  evidently  closed.  It  is  true 
that  there  is  still  a  duality  between  knowledge  and  the  things 
known.  But  the  crux  of  truth  problem  becomes  the  analysis 
of  the  relations  between  two  physical  things,  between  speech-reac- 
tions, and  the  things  to  which  they  refer. 

Coming  then  to  a  study  of  the  relation  of  knowledge  to  its  ob- 
ject, it  will  be  well  to  remind  ourselves  of  the  central  difficulty 
with  which  our  account  must  cope  if  it  is  to  be  successful.  The 
discussion  of  correspondence  theories  of  truth  has  definitely  shown 
that  their  great  weakness  lies  in  their  inability  to  explain  how  a 
particular  piece  of  knowledge,  a  particular  proposition,  as  it  were, 
selects  the  particular  fact  in  terms  of  which  its  truth  value  is  to 
be  determined.  It  has  been  claimed  that  apart  from  some  such 
notion  as  the  intention  or  internal  meaning  of  a  proposition,  it  is 
impossible  to  understand  error.  For  if  error  is  failure  to  cor- 
respond with  something,  we  need  some  intention  whose  frustration 
shall  constitute  failure. 

How  then  is  every  judgment  uniquely  related  to  the  specific 
fact  for  which  it  stands?  Let  us  begin  with  what  have  been  called 
judgments  of  perception.  Redefining  this  notion  in  our  own  terms, 


TRUTH  AS  CORRESPONDENCE  187 

such  judgments  are  those  where  the  stimulus  of  the  speech-reac- 
tion is  that  to  which  the  judgment  has  reference.  I  see  a  colored 
patch,  and  respond  by  saying  "that  is  red."  I  see  my  desk  light 
burning,  and  the  muscles  of  my  vocal  organs  are  innervated  to 
make  the  assertion  "the  light  is  burning."  In  such  cases  the  rela- 
tion between  the  judgment  and  its  object  seems  sufficiently  clear. 
It  is  the  relation  of  response  to  stimulus.  The  object  is  the  cause 
of  the  judgment,  the  causal  nexus  taking  an  intricate  path  through 
the  nervous  ganglia.  So  far  everything  is  simple  enough.  But 
as  soon  as  we  pass  from  judgments  of  this  type  we  find  a  much  more 
complex  situation.  Let  us  take  two  examples. 

Suppose  a  friend  of  mine  has  assured  me  that  he  turned  out 
my  desk  light.  Then,  when  I  enter  the  room  and  find  it  burning, 
my  reaction  may  take  the  form  of  asserting  "he's  a  liar."  The 
stimulus  comes  in  over  a  different  cortical  set,  and  issues  in  a  dif- 
ferent response.  Or  again,  take  the  judgment  "Julius  Caesar 
crossed  the  Rubicon."  Here  the  stimulus  will  probably  be  letters 
on  a  printed  page.  In  both  instances  the  immediate  stimulus  is  in 
a  sense  irrelevant.  How  then  is  the  judgment  related  to  its  object? 

The  general  principle  of  explanation  in  both  cases  is  the  same. 
When  I  see  the  light  burning  and  react  with  an  assertion  about 
my  friend,  the  total  stimulus  is  not  merely  the  impact  of  the 
ethereal  vibrations  upon  my  retina.  It  is  this  impact  and  in  addi- 
tion the  words  of  my  friend.  And  my  neural  set  is  such  that  I 
react  with  regard  to  the  latter  but  not  the  former.  And  when  I 
assert  that  Caesar  crossed  the  Rubicon,  I  am  reproducing  the  origi- 
nal reaction  made  by  observers  two  thousand  years  ago,  who  saw 
him  splash  through  the  stream  and  found  in  the  sight  a  stimulus 
to  the  response,  "He  has  crossed  the  Rubicon!"  The  situation  is 
that  of  the  psychological  investigator  who  tabulates  the  results  of 
experiments  he  has  never  personally  made.  He  is  dealing  with  re- 
sponses whose  stimuli  have  never  gone  across  his  own  nervous 
system.  But  the  whole  significance  of  these  responses  is  their  rela- 
tion to  just  these  stimuli. 

As  has  been  pointed  out,  this  is  nothing  but  a  very  general  ex- 
planation. But  to  demand  very  much  more  would  not  be  reason- 
able. Little  is  known  as  yet  of  the  means  by  which  the  nervous 
system  makes  selections  from  and  performs  integrations  upon  the 
vast  number  of  stimuli  which  come  in  all  the  time.  But  psychology 
and  neurology  are  decidedly  justified  in  assuming  that  this  enor- 
mously complex  mechanism  performs  the  task  somehow.  This  as- 
sumption is  the  only  hope  of  any  sort  of  scientific  explanation  of 
our  mental  life,  and  it  provides  an  excellent  programme  for  re- 
search. It  is  the  best  we  have.  Without  it  we  are  reduced  to  sheer 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

miracle.  And  for  philosophy  the  advantage  of  dealing  with  the 
relation  between  knowledge  and  its  objects  along  this  line  is  that 
it  keeps  us  in  touch  with  the  best  scientific  developments,  and  at 
least  gives  us  the  assurance  that  we  are  dealing  with  facts  rather 
than  fiction,  even  though  our  detailed  knowledge  of  those  facts 
may  be  very  partial. 

Thus  to  sum  up,  every  judgment  is  uniquely  related  to  its  ob- 
ject by  virtue  of  the  fact  that  it  is  a  response  to  which  the  object 
in  question  has  been  or  is  the  stimulus.  A  judgment  may  not  be 
immediately  occasioned  by  the  presence  of  the  object  to  which  it 
refers — for  instance  it  may  be  occasioned  by  a  printed  record. 
This  is  due  to  the  organization  of  our  neural  mechanism,  which 
enables  us  to  effect  vast  economies  in  living.  But  always  we  can 
push  back  to  an  ultimate  stopping  place  where  the  stimulus  and 
the  speech-reaction  are  brought  together  in  time  and  space. 

This  analysis  makes  it  possible  for  us  to  define  truth  in  terms 
of  correspondence,  and  at  the  same  time  to  give  an  account  of  error. 
Fundamental  to  this  account  is  the  notion  of  a  normally  function- 
ing nervous  system. 

For  a  judgment  is  true  when  it  is  the  response  of  a  normal 
organism  to  a  given  stimulus.  Suppose  I  say  "Napoleon's  tomb 
is  in  Paris."  Let  us  assume  that  1  have  read  these  words  some- 
where. Pushing  back  along  the  chain  of  recorded  responses  of 
which  the  printed  symbols  that  I  saw  were  the  last,  I  come  finally 
to  the  place  where  the  original  observer,  who  started  the  whole 
series,  stood.  I  am  directed  to  a  particular  locus,  and  there  I  re- 
ceive a  stimulus  that  issues  in  the  response,  "Yes,  Napoleon's  tomb 
is  in  Paris."  And  this  it  is  which  constitutes  the  truth  of  the 
judgment.  But  suppose  I  read  "Napoleon's  tomb  is  in  Berlin." 
Then  I  am  directed  to  another  locus,  where  I  receive  another  stimu- 
lus, which  issues  in  the  response  "No,  Napoleon's  tomb  is  not  in 
Berlin."  This  means  that  the  original  judgment  was  false.  The 
chain  of  recorded  responses  always  directs  us  to  some  specific  locus. 
This  is  the  function  of  what  has  sometimes  been  called  the  inten- 
tion or  "internal  meaning"  of  the  judgment.  And  the  notion  of 
internal  meaning  has  been  used  to  wreck  the  whole  correspondence 
theory.  In  and  of  itself,  the  notion  seems  to  be  quite  inadmissable. 
The  supposition  that  every  judgment  has  ultimately  two  kinds  of 
meaning  is  one  to  be  avoided  if  at  all  possible.  Such  difficulties 
as  these,  and  their  accompanying  dialectical  objections  to  the  cor- 
respondence theory  of  truth  vanish  as  soon  as  we  bring  to  light  a 
mechanism  which  secures  correlation  between  judgments  and  their 
objects. 


THE  COMPLEX  DILEMMA— A  REJOINDER          189 

It  is  impossible  to  arrive  at  a  satisfactory  account  of  the  objec- 
tive reference  of  judgments  so  long  as  we  consider  nothing  but  the 
judgments  themselves.  In  and  of  themselves  they  are  merely  physi- 
cal facts.  They  are  no  more  and  no  less  mysterious  than  so  many 
chairs  and  tables.  They  are  simply  complexes  of  nervous  discharge 
and  muscular  tension  and  relaxation.  If  we  desire  to  understand 
their  epistemological  function,  we  must  not  consider  them  alone. 
To  do  so  is  to  commit  a  fatal  abstraction.  We  must  take  into  con- 
sideration the  entire  structure  in  which  they  occur — the  organic 
structure  stimulated  by  contacts  with  objects  outside  itself,  and 
responding  to  these  contacts  in  a  thousand  various  ways,  some  of 
which  make  up  what  we  call  knowledge. 

In  closing,  it  may  be  well  to  say  a  word  as  to  the  bearing  of 
this  point  of  view  upon  epistemology  as  a  whole.  Bertrand  Rus- 
sell is  responsible  for  introducing  into  philosophy  a  technique  which 
in  a  measure  deserves  to  be  called  scientific.  By  applying  the 
notions  and  methods  of  symbolic  logic  it  is  undeniably  possible  to 
get  a  very  sharp  definition  of  certain  issues,  and  consequently  to 
arrive  at  definite  solutions  of  detailed  problems.  But  the  differ- 
ence between  modern  science  and  philosophy  is  something  more 
than  a  mere  matter  of  technique.  It  is  a  difference  in  point  of 
view.  Science  is  objective,  and  philosophy,  in  large  measure,  is 
subjective.  Russell's  own  distinction  between  knowledge  by  ac- 
quaintance and  knowledge  by  description  is  essentially  subjective. 
Philosophy  can  not  become  truly  scientific  till  it  becomes  objective 
through  and  through.  And  a  most  important  step  in  this  direction 
is  to  adopt  an  objective  point  of  view  in  studying  the  knowledge- 
situation. 

JAMES  L.  MURSELL. 

PAINESVILLE,  OHIO. 

THE  COMPLEX  DILEMMA— A  REJOINDER 

I  REGRET  that  absence  from  the  country  has  prevented  my  giv- 
ing earlier  attention  to  Professor  Brogan's  criticism1  of  my 
article  on  the  complex  dilemma,2  since  it  contains  a  serious  misrepre- 
sentation. 

The  "exact  meaning"  of  my  criticism  of  the  dilemma  is  said  to 
be  contained  in  the  following  dilemma:  "If  the  minor  and  the  con- 
clusion are  exclusive  alternatives,  the  argument  is  fallacious ;  and  if 
the  minor  is  exclusive  and  the  conclusion  is  non-exclusive  then  the 
argument  is  redundant.  But  either  the  minor  and  the  conclusion 

1  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XVIII,  pp.  566-7. 

2  Ibid.,  pp.  244-6. 


190  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

are  exclusive,  or  the  minor  is  exclusive  and  the  conclusion  is  nou 
exclusive.  Therefore  the  argument  is  fallacious  or  redundant." 
And  Professor  Brogan  adds:  "It  is  perfectly  obvious  that  the  minor 
premise  here  is  false,  because  it  overlooks  the  possibility  that  both 
the  minor  and  the  conclusion  may  be  treated  as  being  formally  non- 
exclusive alternatives.  If  this  treatment  is  given,  the  complex 
dilemma  is  neither  fallacious  nor  redundant." 

The  reader  who  cares  to  refer  to  my  article  will  see  that  these 
remarks  are  wholly  misapplied.  So  far  is  it  from  being  true  that  I 
did  not  consider  the  last-mentioned  possibility,  that  I  showed  ex- 
plicitly that  in  that  case  the  argument  reduces  to  a  familiar  form  of 
sorites.  When  Professor  Brogan  concludes  that  "the  non-exclusive 
interpretation  of  disjunction  is  required  for  the  complex  dilemma," 
he  is  merely  restating  my  own  contention. 

There  is  one  point  in  the  criticism  which  is  well  taken.  The 
example  of  a  complex  destructive  dilemma,  which  I  quoted  from 
Whately  and  Jevons,  was  badly  chosen  for  my  purpose.  As  under- 
stood by  Whately  it  was  merely  redundant,  and  as  interpreted  by 
Jevons  it  was  entirely  correct.  It  is  not  quite  accurate,  however, 
to  say  of  Whately  that,  like  Jevons,  he  "carefully  and  explicitly 
defended  the  non-exclusive  interpretation  of  'or'."  Whately  held 
that  in  most  cases  the  exclusive  interpretation  is  called  for,  but  that 
sometimes  (depending  on  the  context)  the  alternatives  are  to  be 
taken  as  non-exclusive.  Accordingly,  in  his  account  of  the  dilemma 
two  types  appear.  On  the  one  hand,  it  is  explicitly  recognized  that 
the  minor  is  sometimes  not  a  strict  disjunction;  and  on  the  other 
hand,  in  the  construction  of  various  examples,  care  is  evidently  taken 
to  make  the  minor  a  strict  disjunction.  This  is  the  case  with  the 
example  which  I  quoted.  It  is  also  the  case  with  the  following. 
"Either  they  [the  blest  in  heaven]  will  have  no  desires,  or  have  them 
fully  gratified."  "He  [JSschines]  either  joined  [in  the  public  re- 
joicings], or  not."  Furthermore,  there  is  no  suggestion  in  Whately 's 
account  that  where  the  minor  is  thus  clearly  intended  as  a  strict  dis- 
junction, the  conclusion  requires  a  different  interpretation.* 

This  point  is  historically  of  some  importance,  because  it  is  tc 
Whately  that  the  theory  of  the  dilemma  in  its  present  form  is  directlj 
due ;  and  it  is  probably  to  the  imperfect  clearness  of  his  account  that 
the  current  misunderstanding  of  the  topic  is  to  be  traced.4 

THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA. 

BRYN  MAWR  COLLEGE. 

»  Elements  of  Logic,  London,  1848,  pp.  108-110. 

«  Thus  Bain,  who  draws  upon  Whately,  interprets  the  disjunction  strictly, 
without  suspecting  that  he  has  modified  his  borrowings  in  any  way.  Cf.  Logic, 
London,  1910,  Vol.  I,  pp.  119,  121. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  191 

BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  Reign  of  Relativity.    Viscount  HALDANE.    London :  John  Mur- 
ray.   1921.    Pp.  xxiii  +  430. 

Lord  Haldane's  volume  is  a  clear  and  timely  presentation  of  the 
general  standpoint  of  objective  idealism  in  the  light  of  the  science 
and  culture  of  today;  it  falls  readily  within  the  comprehension  of 
all  seriously  interested  in  philosophy,  but  without  any  sacrifice  of 
essentials  or  evasion  of  difficulties.  It  is  unfortunate  that  the  mean- 
ing of  relativity,  like  that  of  idealism  itself,  has  become — quite  apart 
from  the  scientific  theory — extremely  vague  and  confused.  Hal- 
dane's own  use  of  the  term  is  best  described  as  the  explication  of  the 
principle  of  "degrees  of  reality."  "The  distinction  between  ap- 
pearance and  reality  becomes  one  of  degrees  towards  full  compre- 
hension. Conceptions  mould  the  experience  in  which  they  are  ap- 
plied. Through  our  conceptions  we  isolate,  but  we  isolate  only 
special  aspects  of  reality. ' '  These  aspects,  that  is,  never  represent  so 
many  "separately  existing  and  independent  realities";1  but  sepa- 
rateness  is  repudiated  not  in  any  subjective  fashion,  but  with  refer- 
ence to  experience  and  to  reality  as  a  whole.2 

It  is  especially  noteworthy,  in  view  of  recent  discussion,  that 
this  initial  position  is  conjoined  with  an  unambiguous  realism;  for 
realism  can  find  its  fullest  development,  I  think,  only  in  an  alliance 
with  an  idealism  as  truly  objective  as  itself.3  The  question  is 
obviously  too  wide  for  consideration  here;  but  Haldane's  position 
is  perfectly  definite.  "What  is  before  us  is  there,  and  is  independent 
of  the  particular  onlookers  who  are  present  along  with  it."  Thus 
subjectivism  is  excluded;  and  with  it  goes  all  false  abstraction; 
for  "it  is  discoverable  for  us  only  by  means  of  observation  and 
experiment,  and  not  by  a  priori  reasoning.  .  .  .  The  conception  of 
an  electron  may  or  may  not  be  final,  but  it  indicates  what  is  recognized 
as  a  real  complex  of  actual  objective  factors."4  On  these  points 
Lord  Haldane,  to  a  marked  degree,  endorses  Dr.  Whitehead's  con- 
tentions in  his  Concept  of  Nature.5  But  this  agreement  is  qualified 
by  the  criticism  that  Dr.  Whitehead's  final  conclusion  is,  from  the 
strictly  philosophic  point  of  view,  too  absolute,  inasmuch  as  he  "  can 
hardly  claim  to  iave  excluded  nature  from  the  imputation  of  the  in- 

i  Pp.  36,  35. 

2<<  It  is  a  relativity  that  is  not  subjective,  in  the  sense  that  things  are 
only  to  each  of  us  what  they  appear  to  be  "  (p.  37). 

3 ' '  The  difference  between  idealism  and  realism  disappears  in  the  larger 
outlook  that  embraces  the  difference  itself  "  (p.  137). 

*  Pp.  36,  47.  Cf.  p.  211 — ' '  The  world  is  actual  and  independent  of  its 
observer.  ..." 

s  Cf.  this  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIX,  No.  6,  pp.  146-157. 


192  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

gression  of  mind  into  its  constitution"  (p.  81).  I  think,  however, 
that  the  difference  here  is  cutin-ly  one  of  standpoint ;  Dr.  Whitehead, 
"abjuring  metaphysics,"  as  the  scientist  is  entitled  (if  not  indeed 
compelled)  to  do,  regards  natural  phenomena  as,  primd  facie,  outside 
or  beyond  the  observer's  mind;  but  this  in  itself  does  not  imply  any 
discontinuity  between  mind  and  nature  as  interpreted  by  the  more 
inclusive  philosophical  standard. 

From  this  basis  Haldane  develops  his  doctrine  of  relativity  in 
the  sense  that,  universally,  "Knowledge  is  foundations!  of  reality," 
so  that  ' '  we  must  take  account  of  all  the  degrees  and  levels  at  which 
it  appears  and  interpret  them  according  to  their  places  in  the  en- 
tirely. .  .  .  Knowledge  is  foundational  of  both  apprehension  and 
what  is  apprehended. "  6  At  the  first  glance  this  seems  to  confirm  the 
too  general  impression  that  idealism  is  essentially  logical  and  ab- 
stract— a  matter  of  intellect  or  of  discursive  thought.  But  it  is  an 
outstanding  merit  of  this  volume  that  such  an  erroneous  interpreta- 
tion of  idealism  is  emphatically  disclaimed.  "Knowledge"  has  the 
fullest  possible  significance.  It  is  equivalent  to  mind,  or  to  ex- 
perience, as  one  continuous,  immanent,  and  infinitely  diversified 
whole.  It  is  "ultimately  one  and  indivisible.  .  .  .  Mind,  in  the 
fullest  meaning,  is  foundational  to  reality.  .  .  .  We  have  to  inter- 
pret knowledge  in  no  narrow  sense.  It  will  have  to  extend  not  only 
to  notions  but  to  feelings."  Experience  consists  in  short  of  "the 
dynamic  activity  of  mind  .  .  .  dynamic  and  not  static,  and  is  in  its 
real  nature  subject  yet  more  distinctly  than  substance."7 

The  principle  of  relativity,  thus  interpreted,  is  classical.  But 
Haldane  gives  it  a  thoroughly  independent  and  individual  considera- 
tion in  its  bearing  upon  science  and  religion,  society  and  art,  which 
should  do  much  to  clear  away  the  distortions  and  misunderstandings 
which  inevitably  gather  around  every  great  historic  system.  Both 
the  exponents  of  idealism  and  its  more  recent  opponents  are  sub- 
jected to  vigorous  and  effective  criticism,  which  may  be  summarized 
in  the  contention  that,  alike  in  the  case  of  Bosanquet,  Pringle-Pat- 
tison  and  the  New-Realists,  the  full  implications  of  the  finitude  of 
knowledge  are  not  realized  and  developed ;  but  this  more  controver- 
sial feature  of  the  volume  is  best  left  to  the  consideration  of  the 
writers  concerned. 

The  lengthy  section  dealing  with  the  recent  development  of  the 
purely  scientific  theory  of  relativity  is  naturally  of  special  interest. 
The  outline  of  the  theory  itself  is  as  free  from  technicality  as  Is 
possible  in  dealing  with  a  subject  so  abstract,  and  should  be  helpful 

« Pp.  124,  137. 

'  Pp.  126,  128,  147,  155,  166. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  193 

to  those  who  still  find  it  as  a  whole  obscure.  But  when  we  turn 
from  exposition  to  interpretation  it  seems  to  me  that  Haldane,  though 
to  a  far  less  degree  than  previous  writers,  tends  to  read  too  much 
into  the  theory  in  both  its  scientific  and  philosophic  aspects.  Its 
strictly  scientific  importance  is  so  fundamental  that  some  degree 
of  overstatement — for  which,  however,  its  originators  are  not  them- 
selves responsible — was  inevitable,  and  here  a  reaction  is  to  be  ex- 
pected. Haldane 's  objectivist  standpoint  safeguards  him  from  the 
tendency  to  argue  that  scientific  relativity  implies  philosophic  sub- 
jectivity; "there  is  not  one  system  of  space-time  in  contrast  with 
which  others  are  subjective"  (p.  402)  ;  and  he  employs  Einstein's 
results  merely  by  way  of  illustrating  his  general  principle  (p.  39). 
But  still  he  appears  to  me  to  err  almost  as  seriously  in  another  direc- 
tion, inasmuch  as  he  omits  to  distinguish  definitely  enough  between 
space  and  time,  as  such,  and  spatio-temporal  measurement  systems,8 
and  therefore  fails  to  recognize  sufficiently  that  in  passing  from  the 
latter,  with  which  the  scientific  theory  is  concerned,  to  the  former, 
which  are  the  main  objects  of  philosophical  speculation,  we  are 
dealing  with  vitally  different  aspects  of  the  real  whole.  The  con- 
sequence is  that  he  falls  here  into  the  error  against  which  he  con- 
stantly warns  us — "the  blunder  of  confusing  our  categories"  (p.  37)  ; 
and  similarly  he  interprets  the  purely  scientific  conclusions  too  liter- 
ally, without  due  allowance  for  what  may,  from  the  analogy  with 
Kant's  general  method,  be  called  the  als  o~b  element  in  the  entire 
theory.  Its  principles,  that  is,  are  very  largely  methodological ;  they 
are  adopted,  and  they  are  valid,  only  for  certain  abstract  purposes  of 
mathematical  calculation  and  physical  theory,  so  that  (at  least  as 
matters  stand  at  present)  it  is  illegitimate  to  regard  them  as  true 
apart  from  certain  fundamental  qualifications  necessary  when  a 
wider  range  of  phenomena  is  considered.  This  applies,  e.g.,  to  the 
treatment  of  gravitation  on  p.  57. 

Another  somewhat  perplexing  feature  of  Haldane 's  position  is 
his  emphasis  on  the  discontinuity  of  our  categories.  A  consistent 
relativism  demands,  I  think,  an  ideal  continuity;  and  much,  if  not 
indeed  all,  of  the  value  of  Einstein's  methods  lies  in  the  fuller 
continuity  which  they  import  into  physical  theory.  Continuity  is 
indeed  clearly  recognized.  The  result  of  the  development  of  knowl- 
edge "has  been  accomplishing  itself  continuously"  (p.  417),  although 
the  categories  which  we  actually  employ  are  as  a  matter  of  fact 

8  This  fundamental  distinction,  curiously  enough,  receives  due  emphasis  from 
the  scientists  themselves.  Cf.  this  JOURNAL,  XVIII.,  pp.  214,  215.  Also  Ed- 
dington,  Nature,  Feb.  17,  1921,  p.  804:  "  Worldwide  time  is  a  mathematical 
system;  it  has  not  any  metaphysical  significance." 


194  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

seriously  lacking  in  interconnection.  But  idealist  logic  would,  I 
think,  regard  this  defect  as  due  merely  to  our  limited  knowledge. 
Haldane,  however,  seems  to  regard  discontinuity  not  only  as  oc- 
casional and  transitory,  but  even  as  essential.  He  speaks  of  "levels 
or  degrees  in  knowledge  which  have  relations  to  each  other,  but 
are  not  reducible  to  each  other.  For  they  are  ultimate.  .  .  .  The  ac- 
tual exhibits  itself  in  orders  irreducible  to  each  other.  ...  A  living 
being  that  knows  seems  to  belong  to  an  order  quite  different  in  kind 
from  that  of  one  that  lives  without  knowing.  .  .  .  Mechanism  and 
life  belong  to  different  orders  neither  of  which  is  explicable  in  the 
terms  that  belong  to  the  other."9  If  this  is  literally  true  any  con- 
tinuous and  progressive  development  of  knowledge  would  surely 
be  impossible;  but  when  we  consider  its  actual  character,  what  we 
seem  to  find  is  an  unceasing  growth  in  continuity  which  goes  on,  in 
principle,  without  limit ; 10  unless  of  course  we  define  our  categories 
to  begin  with  so  that  they  become  mutually  exclusive,  and  ' '  mechan- 
ism," e.g.,  means  "non-living"  while  "life"  means  "non-mechani- 
cal." Haldane  bases  his  idealistic  relativity  on  "The  Hegelian 
Principle"  (chap.  XV) ;  and  I  welcome  his  plea  for  the  closer  study 
of  Hegel,  together  with  his  protest  against  the  prevailing  miscon- 
ception of  his  system.  "No  philosophical  doctrine  has  been  more 
misrepresented  or  given  to  the  world  in  a  more  distorted  form  than 
has  been  Hegelianism  in  current  literature"  (p.  344).  But  the 
basal  principle  of  Hegel's  Logic  is  the  continuity  of  the  transition 
from  category  to  category ; "  so  that  if  we  are  to  take  the  state- 
ments just  quoted  as  really  typical,  there  seems  to  be  a  fundamental 
discrepancy  between  Haldane 's  position  and  that  of  Hegel;  the 
latter,  however,  appears  to  be  more  firmly  established  by  each  ad- 
vance in  the  content  of  knowledge. 

But  there  is  ample  room  for  differences  of  opinion  here,  and 
Lord  Haldane  would  be  the  last  to  expect  complete  unanimity.  His 
volume,  taken  as  -a  whole,  is  a  very  valuable  and  weighty  contribu- 
tion to  philosophical  literature. 

J.  E.  TURNER. 
LIVERPOOL,  ENO. 

»Pp.  128,  132,  147,  161. 

10  Cf.  p.  415.     ' '  The  capacity  of  man  to  interpret  is  unlimited  in  its  range, 
because  the  range  of  mind  is  unlimited  in  its  power  of  framing  general  con- 
ceptions."    But  does  not  this  in  itself  imply  that  categories  are  not  (in  prin- 
ciple of  course)  ultimately  irreducible? 

11  Cf.  McTaggart,  Studies  in  the  Hegelian  Dialectic,  sees.   112-114,  and 
Commentary,  sec.  12. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS         195 

JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

SCIENTIA.  June,  1921.  Ten  Great  Epochs  in  the  History  of 
Mathematics  (pp.  417-428):  DAVID  EUGENE  SMITH  (New  York).- 
Attractive  little  sketch  of  the  history  of  mathematics  from  a  partic- 
ular point  of  view.  La  contribution  que  les  divers  pays  ont  donnee 
aux  progres  de  la  physique.  II.  Physique  energetique  et  physique 
electronique  (pp.  429-442)  :  ABEL  KEY  (Paris). -On  the  basis  of  the 
earlier  discovered  thermodynamic  laws  was  built  up  in  the  late 
nineteenth  century  a  science  of  energetics,  a  physics  without  hypo- 
theses either  atomic  or  kinetic.  But  it  was  on  the  whole  infertile  in 
new  discoveries,  and  atomism  came  back  to  its  own  again  with  the 
electron  theories  of  the  twentieth  century.  All  the  different  branches 
of  physics — and  chemistry  as  well — have  now  reached  a  new  syn- 
thesis and  system,  one  science  instead  of  a  group  of  partly  analogous 
sciences ;  while  the  work  of  developing  it  has  become  even  more  truly 
international  than  ever  before,  though  the  English  still  think  in  terms 
of  concrete  models,  the  Germans  in  abstract  mathematics,  and  the 
French  and  Italians  pursue  a  middle  course.  La  constitution  de  I'in- 
dividualite.  I.  L 'individuality  physiologique  (pp.  443-452)  :  Au- 
GUSTO  Pi  SUNER  (Barcelona)  .-Every  biological  individual  is  capable 
of  reproducing  itself,  and  is  unique  not  only  in  outward  form  but 
also  in  chemical  constitution.  Problemes  financiers  d'apres  guerre. 
I.  Dettes  publiques  et  charges  fiscales  (pp.  453-472) :  CORRADO 
GINI  (Padua). -Excellent  survey  of  the  usual  means  now  employed 
to  raise  the  national  revenue,  with  the  merits  of  each.  Reviews  of 
Scientific  Books  and  Periodicals. 
Levy-Bruhl,  Lucien.  La  Mentalite  Primitive.  Paris:  Felix  Alcan. 

1922.    Pp.  537.     25  fr. 

More,  Paul  Elmer.     The  Religion  of  Plato.     Princeton:  University 
Press.    London :  Oxford  University  Press.    1921.    Pp.  xii  +  352. 
Piccoli,  Raffaello.     Benedetto  Croce:  An  Introduction  to  his  Phi- 
losophy.   New  York :  Harcourt,  Brace  &  Co.    1922.    Pp.  xi  +  315. 
Reyburn,  Hugh  A.    The  Ethical  Theory  of  Hegel :  A  Study  of  the 
Philosophy  of  Right.     Oxford:   Clarendon  Press.     1921.     Pp. 
xx      268. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

The  Aristotelian  Society  met  in  London  on  February  6,  1922, 
Professor  Wildon  Carr  in  the  chair.  Mr.  A.  H.  Hannay  read  a  paper 
on  "Standards  and  Principles  in  Art,"  a  synopsis  of  which  follows: 

The  problem  of  standards  and  of  objectivity  in  art  is  usually 


196  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

debated  on  the  basis  of  the  alternatives  of  standards-and-objectivity 
or  no-standards-and-subjectivity ;  and  no  third  possibility  is  envis- 
aged. Neither  alternative  being  satisfactory,  the  position  is  a 
stalemate.  Mr.  Bal four's  attitude  in  his  Romanes  lecture  is  typical. 
It  is  true  that  the  standard  and  rule  must  be  rejected.  They  involve 
a  vicious  circle  and  enjoy  only  a  counterfeit  stability.  No  mediating 
criterion  can  be  set  up.  Each  new  and  individual  work  of  art 
carries  with  it  its  own  individual  and  original  awareness.  This  view 
however  does  not  necessitate  a  lapse  into  subjectivism,  if  it  is  realized 
that  the  awareness  or  taste  is  itself  a  striving  for  objectivity  and 
Tightness.  The  very  search  for  standards  is  itself  the  outcome  of 
this  incessant  quest  for  right  taste.  While  this  particular  search 
has  proved  fruitless,  it  is  a  half  truth  to  say  that  nothing  can  be 
achieved  by  means  of  reflection,  definition  and  analysis.  Beauty  is 
not  entirely  unique  and  indefinable.  It  is  a  process,  a  constructing, 
and  can  be  differentiated  from  other  processes,  such  as  history, 
science,  philosophy.  Actually,  modern  criticism  is  full  of  psycholog- 
ical analyses  which  definitely  involve  reflective  principles.  These 
however  are  distinct  from  the  old  standards,  inasmuch  as  they  do 
not  pretend  to  anticipate  the  individual  content  of  works  of  art. 
Nevertheless  the  same  question  arises  regarding  them  as  regarding 
standards.  Do  they  precede,  accompany  or  follow  upon  esthetic 
creation  and  appreciation?  And  if  they  follow  upon  it,  what  is 
their  value?  It  is  the  commonly  accepted  view  that  they  are  a 
later  product.  This  view  has  been  stated  very  lucidly  and  trench- 
antly by  Benedetto  Croce  and  is  very  plausible.  Yet  history  does 
not  confirm  it  and  it  does  not  explain  the  fact  that  criticism  clarifies 
taste  and  is  expected  to  do  so.  Croce 's  own  admirable  criticism  is 
a  good  instance.  It  is  therefore  suggested  that  the  process  imagina- 
tion-principle is  not  a  passage  from  one  independent  activity  to 
another,  but  a  development  requiring  from  the  start  both  activities 
and  in  which  a  modification  in  one  means  a  modification  in  the  other. 
The  critic  emphasizes  the  universal  element  while  the  artist  empha- 
sizes the  individual  element ;  nevertheless  the  critic  attains  a  clearer 
consciousness  of  the  value  and  significance  of  the  individual  work 
of  art. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  8.  APRIL  13,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


ROMANTICISM  VS.  THE  WORSHIP  OF  FACT 

ECENTLY  a  noted  writer  reiterated  the  ancient  but  fallaci- 
ous  charge  of  subjectivism  against  the  romantic  attitude. 
The  dispute  normally  arises  in  the  following  way:  The  romantic 
endeavors  to  escape  from  the  world  of  the  actual  into  that  of  fancy, 
or  more  specifically  into  the  realm  of  esthetic  and  speculative  im- 
agination. The  critic,  however,  interprets  this  attitude  as  an  un- 
willingness to  submit  to  outward  fact  and  accuses  the  romantic  of 
a  desire  to  withdraw  into  a  world  of  his  own  creation. 

The  indictment  rests  on  a  confusion  between  the  actual  and  the 
real.  The  critic  begins  with  a  fallacious  identification  of  the  real 
with  the  actual  and  then  goes  on  to  describe  any  breaking  loose 
from  the  latter  into  the  world  of  imagination  as  a  detachment  from 
the  objective  and  a.  retreat  into  the  subjective.  But  it  is  only  a 
vulgar  preference  or  extreme  naivete  that  could  lead  one  to  limit 
reality  to  the  actual ;  over  and  above  the  actual,  there  is  the  field  of 
subsistence,  of  ideal  entities,  of  forms,  of  possibilities;  and  the 
romantic  imagination  is  not  vain  dreaming  but  an  extension  of  the 
area  of  knowledge  itself  beyond  perception  into  the  realm  of  these 
ideal  essences. 

It  was  the  distinctive  merit  of  Leibniz  to  have  pointed  out  with 
clearness  that  besides  the  actual  there  is  also  the  world  of  possibili- 
ties, inhabited  by  entities  that  are  real  though  not  existent.  Leib- 
niz, in  commenting  upon  the  common-sense  view  that  "heavy  bodies 
really  exist  and  act,  but  possibilities  or  essences  anterior  to  exist- 
ence or  apart  from  it,  are  imaginary  or  fictitious"  urges  that 
"neither  these  essences  nor  what  are  called  eternal  truths  regard- 
ing these  essences  are  fictitious  but  that  they  exist  in  a  certain  re- 
gion (if  I  may  so  call  it)  of  ideas,  that  is  to  say,  in  God  Himself."  1 

Now,  the  romantic  escape  from  the  actual  is  but  a  transfer  of 
residence  into  the  realm  of  possibilities.  Indeed,  romanticism  is 
to  art  what  pure  logic  is  to  thought;  both  are  other-worldly,  and 
differ  only  in  the  fact  that,  whereas  the  former  is  seeking  beauty, 
the  latter  is  in  quest  of  intellectual  values  in  the  universe  of  all 
possible  worlds.  Hence,  far  from  being  subjectivistic,  romanticism 
is  a  projection  of  the  self  into  the  objective ;  far  from  being  a  flight 
i  Quoted  from  the  Essay  on  the  Ultimate  Origination  of  Things. 

197 


198  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

into  the  void  of  the  unreal,  romanticism  is  a  sharing,  along  with 
God,  in  the  contemplation  of  the  vast  landscape  of  all  possible 
worlds. 

It  is  the  "realist"  himself  that  must  be  charged  with  subjectivism. 
For,  by  insisting  that  attention  be  confined  to  the  actual,  the  realist 
manifests  a  limitation  of  interest  to  himself  and  to  his  immediate 
surroundings.  After  all,  the  world  of  actuality  has  no  intrinsic 
advantages  over  the  world  of  possibility ;  we  come  to  like  the  former 
quite  unreflectively  because  we  find  ourselves  in  it,  as  we  like  our 
brothers  and  sisters,  or  our  country.  To  be  transported  into  the 
possible  is  to  be  taken  out  of  ourselves  and  our  own,  and  the  realist, 
refusing  as  he  does  to  leave  the  borders  of  his  spiritual  birthplace, 
betrays  an  intellectual  provincialism;  his  mind  remains  untrav- 
elled.  But  the  romantic  temperament  is  adventuresome  and  free, 
launching  bold  expeditions  into  unexplored  regions  of  possibility, 
all  the  while  going  about,  not  in  the  fashion  of  a  Baedecker  tour- 
ist, but  immersing  itself  in  the  new  regions  and  investigating  them 
with  an  open  mind,  unhampered  by  the  prejudices  of  the  little  bit 
of  actuality  into  which  it  has  been  born. 

The  realist  suffers  from  inertia  of  mind;  he  is  too  indolent  to 
move  about.  But  romanticism  is  the  mind  become  active  and  rest- 
less, for  fancy  is  like  blazing  coal  in  the  engine  of  the  soul.  Thus, 
the  realist's  world  is  poor  and  narrow,  devoid  of  the  wealth  and 
variety  of  the  romantic  scenery.  And  if  the  poet's  dictum  that 
"he  does  not  England  know  who  only  England  knows"  be  true, 
then,  by  analogy,  the  realist  knows  not  even  his  corner  of  actuality 
well,  because  he  has  not  contemplated  it  in  the  light  of  other  pos- 
sibilities. 

The  fundamental,  though  tacit,  assumption  of  the  defenders  of 
realism  is  that  actuality  possesses  worth  as  such  and  that  roman- 
ticism is  at  a  great  disadvantage  for  its  neglect  of  the  actual. 
Anselm,  even  Leibniz  himself,  maintained  that  actuality  is  a  requisite 
of  perfection  and  the  transition  from  possibility  to  realization  an 
absolute  gain.  Now,  for  one  thing,  Kant  has  refuted  Anselm  by 
showing  that  actuality  adds  nothing  to  possibility.  In  fact,  there 
is  something  essentially  accidental  about  actuality.  Abstractly, 
any  causal  law  is  as  possible  as  any  other;  yet  one  is  realized  and 
the  others  are  not.  There  is  no  reason  why  dead  people  should  not 
talk,  but  they  don't;  there  is  no  reason  why  the  sun  should  rise; 
it  simply  does  rise  and  keeps  on  rising,  inexplicably,  every  morn- 
ing. Existence  is  therefore  lacking  the  dignity  bestowed  by  neces- 
sity. 

Moreover,  do  we  not  all  admit  that  distance  lends  enchantment — 


ROMANTICISM  VS.  THE  WORSHIP  OF  FACT         199 

distance  in  time,  distance  from  the  present,  in  other  words,  remote- 
ness from  the  actual?  The  past  is  beautiful  because  it  represents 
that  portion  of  reality  which  has  gone  out  of  time  into  eternity. 
That  spatio-temporal  reality  is  at  best  a  poor  affair,  is  evidenced  by 
the  fact  that  reason  in  the  guise  of  science  is  engaged  in  a  con- 
tinued effort  to  patch  things  up,  to  fill  up  vast  gaps  by  correspond- 
ingly vast  assumptions,  introducing  the  hypothesis  of  uniformity  to 
explain  away  the  apparent  diversity,  sewing  up  the  ragged  edges 
of  events  with  the  thread  of  causal  law,  trying  to  compensate  for 
the  coarse  exterior  of  the  stream  of  happenings  by  constructing 
behind  apearances  a  conceptual  world  of  points  and  atoms,  so  much 
so  that  virtually  the  larger  part  of  what  common-sense  and  science 
call  reality  is  nothing  but  intellectual  construction. 

But  may  not  actuality  claim  a  certain  "robustness"  and  "con- 
creteness"  denied  to  the  world  of  pure  ideas?  Even  that  is  doubt- 
ful. The  robustness  of  the  actual  is  of  a  hectic  hue  and  deceptive 
like  the  color  on  a  feverish  face  or  the  energy  exhibited  by  one  who 
is  intoxicated.  For  the  more  penetrating  and  intense  the  intellect- 
ual vision,  the  more  does  the  actual  fade  into  a  shadow,  as  Plato 
came  to  see,  until,  in  the  mystical  experience,  it  dissolves  into  an 
illusion.  The  claims  of  fact  upon  our  attention  are  not  of  intrin- 
sic merit  but  of  dominion;  we  must  take  notice  of  the  immediate 
situation  because,  if  we  do  not,  we  suffer.  And  yet  it  is  into  this 
sea  of  fleeting,  chaotic  existence  that  Bergsonian  mysticism  invites 
us  to  plunge — stripped  bare  of  all  clothing  of  intellectual  elabora- 
tion— to  be  drawn  below  by  fickle  currents,  away  from  the  fresh 
and  free  atmosphere  of  creative  thought. 

In  sum,  existence  is  an  evil  and  creation  the  original  sin.  Leib- 
niz himself  recognized  that  a  possibility  can  never  be  realized  as 
such  because  the  receptivity  of  the  world  is  limited.  To  realize  is 
to  weaken,  to  dilute  the  ideal.  That,  as  J.  S.  Mill  complained,  a 
heretic  becomes  a  tyrant  as  soon  as  he  enters  into  power — in  other 
words,  that  one  ceases  to  care  for  freedom  as  soon  as  one  has  at- 
tained it — is  a  vivid  instance  of  the  vicious  effect  of  attempting  to 
transfer  the  ideal  from  the  realm  of  possibility  to  that  of  fact.  The 
question  instinctively  arises,  why  there  should  be  a  world  of  ex- 
istence at  all.  If  we  look  at  the  process  as  a  passage  from  the  pos- 
sible to  the  actual  through  the  mechanism  of  creation,  then  the  prob- 
lem before  us  is  indeed  insoluble.  But  the  situation  is  simplified 
if  we  take  existence  as  granted  and  regard  the  universal  process 
as  one  of  a  gradual  liberation  of  the  possible  from  the  existent.  To 
this  view,  the  law  of  the  dissipation  of  energy  lends  strong  support. 
Obviously,  matter  obstinately  resists  extinction,  yet  the  availability 


200  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  energy  for  work  constantly  diminishes;  in  other  words,  its  abil- 
ity to  embody  new  forms  and  ideas  is  gradually  being  reduced. 
Spurts  of  new  life  and  the  formation  of  new  combinations  indicate 
desperate  efforts  on  the  part  of  the  actual  to  extend  its  hold  upon 
the  ideal;  but  with  the  eventual  cessation  of  work,  foreshadowed 
by  the  so-called  law  of  degeneration,  the  dominion  of  matter  over 
form  will  come  to  an  end,  and  the  realm  of  possibilities  will  no 
longer  suffer  encroachment  from  the  actual. 

In  line  with  this  tendency  are  all  the  noblest  aspirations  of  man 
as  embodied  in  art,  in  religion,  and  in  philosophy.  In  these,  the 
soul  proclaims  itself  an  exile  in  the  actual  and  voices  a  profound 
yearning  to  escape  from  the  immediate  in  time  and  in  space. 
Romanticism,  then,  as  we  have  defined  it,  is  not  by  any  means  an 
isolated  movement.  Philosophy  and  poetry  constitute  preeminent 
instances  of  the  soul  liberating  itself  from  fact  under  the  stimulus, 
in  the  one  case,  of  intellectual  and  in  the  other  of  esthetic  imagina- 
tion. Even  science,  as  we  noted  above,  is  not  a  mirror  of  fact,  but 
an  intellectual  embroidery  upon  it.  And  as  philosophy  expresses 
the  romanticism  of  the  intellect,  so  does  the  attitude  of  faith  repre- 
sent the  romanticism  of  the  will.  For  what  is  this  undying  optim- 
ism in  the  face  of  failure,  this  pathetic  devotion  to  hopeless  causes, 
this  faith  in  the  eventual  doing  of  justice  when  injustice  rules  un- 
checked, this  belief  in  human  beings  and  confidence  in  their  un- 
limited progress,  but  a  vast  construction  of  the  moral  imagination 
upon  the  very  facts  of  failure? 

In  the  long  run,  life  can  not  be  left  wholly  out  of  account; 
after  all,  life  is  one  of  the  many  dreams  and  the  actual  world  one 
of  the  infinite  possible  worlds.  We  should  therefore  school  our 
minds  to  conceive  the  actual  sub  specie  possibilitatis — to  use  it  in- 
deed as  a  stepping-stone  into  the  domain  of  possibility.  For  the 
enlightened  soul  inhabits  a  world  whose  area  embraces  the  actual 
but  extends  far  beyond  it  into  the  subsistent,  and  its  home  is  the 
entire  universe  of  being. 

RAPHAEL  DEMOS. 

CAMBRIDGE,  MASS. 


IN  the  presentation  of  a  scientific  theory  for  philosophical  con- 
sideration, it  is  of  primary  importance  that  the  fundamental 
bases  of  the  theory  be  brought  prominently,  and  indeed  unequivo- 
i  Certain  objections  to  J.  E.  Turner 's  article  ' '  Some  Philosophic  Aspects  of 
Scientific  Relativity,"  this  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XVIII,  No.  8. 


RELATIVITY,  OLD  AND  NEW  201 

cally  to  the  fore,  and  that  the  points  at  which  it  departs  in  its  vital 
essentials  from  previously  held  theories  relating  to  the  same  phe- 
nomena stand  forth  in  unmistakable  relief.  From  this  standpoint 
I  can  not  but  take  exception  to  Mr.  Turner's  presentation,  as  well  as 
to  some  of  his  conclusions. 

In  his  second  paragraph  Mr.  Turner  wisely  says  "...  the  term 
'relativity'  itself  accounts  for  much  of  the  prevailing  confusion," 
and  further,  "Even  its  widest  later  applications  are  concerned  only 
with  the  relative  velocities  of  systems  and  observers,  and  with  the 
mathematical  and  other  scientific  (but  not  philosophic)  implications 
of  these.  .  .  .  The  theory  has  ...  no  bearing  on  the  subjectivity  of 
Time  and  Space."  The  first  quotation  would  suggest  that  an  ex- 
planation of  the  term  "relativity"  in  its  application  under  discus- 
sion is  desirable,  and  this  I  shall  endeavor  to  supply.  The  second 
is  true  only  if  ' '  philosophic ' '  is  used  in  a  very  narrow  sense.  Philo- 
sophy, certainly  if  it  "holds  an  inalienable  lien  on  the  whole  of  ex- 
perience" is  concerned  with  other  aspects  of  time  and  space  than 
their  subjectivity  and  objectivity.  While  relativity  may  throw  no 
additional  light  on  the  question  of  the  degree  of  objectivity  possessed 
by  the  metrical  time  and  space  which  are  mathematically  treated,  it 
introduces  changes  in  our  ideas  as  to  the  relations  between  them,  to 
motion,  and  to  things  in  time  and  space,  which,  even  if  not  "revolu- 
tionary," are  profoundly  different  from  the  classical  conceptions. 
Revolutionary  is  an  hyperbolical  word,  but  the  theory  of  the  relations 
between  space  and  time  required  by  modern  physics  must  command 
philosophical  attention,  though  it  be  characterized  by  a  more  modest 
adjective. 

The  idea  of  "relativity"  in  physics  is  by  no  means  modern,  but 
has  been  assumed  in  Newtonian  mechanics  almost  axiomatically  in 
the  case  of  uniform  motion.  This  "Newtonian  Relativity"  is  the 
relativity  of  the  "man  in  the  street,"  and  in  everyday  language  is 
nothing  more  than  the  statement  that  if  a  person  walks  four  miles 
per  hour  from  the  rear  platform  to  the  front  platform,  of  a  trolley 
car  running  twenty  miles  an  hour,  he  will  cover  ground  at  the  rate 
of  twenty-four  miles  an  hour ;  and  further,  if  a  boy  standing  on  the 
track  in  front  of  the  car  throws  a  stone  at  a  speed  of  one  hundred 
miles  an  hour,  it  will  hit  the  passenger  at  the  speed  of  one  hundred 
and  twenty-four  miles  an  hour.  This  seems  axiomatic  to  the  non- 
scientifically  inclined,  and  in  the  language  of  physics  defines  space 
as  a  region  in  which  Euclidean  geometry  is  valid.  In  such  a  space 
figures  may  be  moved  about  and  rotated  without  change  of  size  or 
shape,  either  while  moving,  or  after  having  changed  their  relative 


202  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOI'JI  Y 

positions;  velocities  are  directly  additive,  and  by  combining  a  suffi- 
cient number  of  finite  velocities,  we  may  exceed  any  specified  velo- 
city. If  we  have  a  record  of  the  motions  of  our  passenger  in  the 
trolley  car  relative  to  the  car  (as  for  instance  the  spots  that  he 
tapped  on  the  floor  with  his  cane,  which  he  is  in  the  habit  of  swing- 
ing every  second  as  he  walks)  we  can  obtain  a  record  of  his  positions 
relative  to  the  track  by  adding  to  the  distance  of  each  spot  from  the 
rear  platform,  the  quantity  obtained  by  multiplying  the  time  of  that 
spot  by  the  velocity  of  the  car,  and  laying  off  the  total  distance  so 
computed  from  the  position  of  the  rear  platform  when  the  car 
started.  If  we  denote  the  distance  from  the  rear  platform  of  the 
car  by  x'  and  that  from  the  station  by  x  we  find  that  x'  =  x  —  vt  (1) 
where  v  is  the  velocity  of  the  car.  The  position  of  the  passenger 
between  the  rails,  and  the  height  above  the  rails  are  not  affected  by 
the  motion  of  the  car,  and  there  is  no  discrepancy  between  the  pas- 
senger's watch  and  the  clock  in  the  station,  provided  that  they 
agreed  at  the  start.  These  facts  are  described  by  the  equations 
y'  =  y,  (2),  z'  =  z  (3),  and  t'  =  t  (4).  The  important  features  of 
this  transformation,  for  our  present  discussion  are: 

(a)  Distances  are  unaltered. 

(6)  Directions  are  unaltered. 

(c)  Velocities  are  directly  additive. 

(d)  The  time  is  entirely  independent  of  the  space  transformation. 

(e)  No  forces  are  introduced  in  one  system  that  were  not  present 

in  the  other. 

It  seems  inherent  to  our  sense  of  physical  things  that  they  should 
be  describable  from  two  systems  of  reference,  i.e.,  from  the  car  and 
from  the  ground,  in  such  a  way  that  certain  properties  which  we 
feel  to  be  fundamental  should  remain  unaltered  in  the  two  descrip- 
tions. In  the  transformation  from  one  system  to  another  which  we 
have  just  described,  i.e.,  one  in  which  the  two  systems  of  reference 
have  a  uniform  velocity  relative  to  each  other,  these  properties  are : 
length,  direction,  mass  and  force.  It  is  important  to  notice  that  no 
velocity  is  invariant.  The  velocity  with  which  the  passanger  is 
covering  the  ground  is  the  sum  of  the  speed  with  which  he  walks  in 
the  car,  and  the  speed  of  the  car. 

The  above  discussion  covers  ''Newtonian  relativity"  in  its  es- 
sentials. It  is  something  so  familiar  that  we  almost  instinctively 
feel  it,  and  the  quantities  that  it  leaves  invariant  we  have  hitherto 
regarded  as  fundamental  in  physics,  and,  in  fact,  as  "objective" 
in  the  same  sense  that  "things"  and  any  relations  between  things 
are  objective.  So  deeply  was  the  idea  of  the  invariance  of  these 
quantities  embedded  in  our  physical  concepts  that  when  new  forces 


RELATIVITY,  OLD  AND  NEW  203 

were  introduced  in  cases  in  which  the  motion  was  not  uniform,  we 
did  not  regard  it  as  a  violation  of  the  principle,  and  we  called  such 
forces  "inertia  forces,"  although  the  question,  "Uniform  relatively 
to  what?  "  was  lightly  avoided.  But  while  the  above  discussion 
is  in  accord  with  everyday  thought,  certain  physical  phenomena 
are  not  in  accord  with  it. 

Within  the  last  hundred  years,  the  results  of  various  experi- 
ments have  forced  us  from  this  delightfully  simple  and  "self-evi- 
dent" relativity.  These  experiments  are  of  two  general  types. 
One  type  shows  that  whether  we  are  moving  toward,  or  receding 
from  a  ray  of  light,  it  approaches  us  with  the  same  relative  velocity. 
From  the  point  of  view  of  classical  mechanics  this  conclusion  is 
little  short  of  astounding,  but  it  is  arrived  at  by  direct  physical 
measurement,  and  must  be  accepted,  at  least  pending  the  results  of 
further  experimental  investigation.  It  also  appears  that  this  is 
not  due  to  the  medium  which  transmits  light  (if  such  there  be) 
being  carried  along  with  us  as  we  move. 

The  other  type  of  experiment  shows  that  the  dimensions  of 
particles  moving  with  velocities  approaching  that  of  light,  vary  in 
a  certain  way  according  to  the  velocity  of  the  system  from  which 
they  are  measured.  An  electron  suffers  a  contraction  in  the  direc- 
tion of  its  motion  relative  to  the  system  of  measurement,  and  its 
mass  increases  as  a  certain  function  of  its  velocity.  Computation 
also  shows  that,  accompanying  these  transformations,  there  must 
be  an  increase  in  the  units  of  time  on  the  moving  electron,  relative 
to  the  units  on  the  observing  system.  These  phenomena  were 
known  as  "The  Lorentz-FitzGerald  Contraction,"  and  it  was  first 
shown  by  Einstein  that  they  depend  not  on  any  peculiarity  of  elec- 
trons, but  on  the  very  act  of  measuring  by  a  means  of  communica- 
tion, between  object  and  observer,  the  velocity  of  which  is  invari- 
ant. 

The  revision  of  the  Newtonian  principle  of  relativity  to  account 
for  these  experimentally  observed  facts  has  been  effected  by  Ein- 
stein in  his  "Special  Theory  of  Relativity."  He  has  shown  that 
all  these  phenomena  are  capable  of  explanation  if  we  drop  the  as- 
sumption of  the  invariance  of  our  supposed  fundamental  physical 
quantities,  and  proceed  on  the  assumption  of  the  invariance  of  the 
velocity  of  light.  When  we  do  this  the  stability  of  our  old  con- 
stants flies  to  the  winds.  The  length  of  our  trolley  car  becomes 
shorter  when  it  is  in  motion  relatively  to  us  than  when  it  is  station- 
ary, and  the  passenger's  embonpoint  suffers  even  more  so,  provided 
he  is  walking  towards  the  front  of  the  car;  also  his  velocity  over 
the  ground  is  a  little  less  than  the  sum  of  his  walking  speed  and 


204  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  speed  of  the  car.    The  equations  of  this  transformation  which 
take  the  place  of  (1)  and  (4)  in  the  Newtonian  theory  are 


and 

(6). 


In  this  transformation  none  of  the  properties  considered  under 
the  former  transformation  holds,  with  the  exception  of  (e).  The 
point  that  might  be  characterized  as  "revolutionary"  is  that  the 
space  and  time  transformations  are  not  independent.  Now  it  is 
true  that  in  previous  physical  theory  four  independent  coordi- 
nates have  been  used  to  describe  an  event,  three  to  establish  a  posi- 
tion in  space,  and  one  to  signify  the  time  of  that  position ;  but  the 
distinction  between  space  and  time  has  always  been  definite.  The 
characteristics  of  space  remained  invariant  in  time,  and  those  of 
time  were  invariant  in  space.  Under  such  conditions  it  was  of  no 
utility  to  complicate  the  discussion  by  saying  that  an  event  was 
specified  by  four  coordinates  in  a  four-dimensional  space-time,  al- 
though this  conception  could  have  been  used  by  any  one  so  inclined. 
The  sense  in  which  this  conception  is  used  in  the  theory  of  relativity 
is,  however,  far  more  fundamental. 

Consider,  for  instance,  our  observation  of  a  cube.  Disregard- 
ing the  effect  of  binocular  vision,  a  cube  may  appear  to  us  as  a 
variety  of  plane  figures,  according  to  our  line  of  sight.  From  one 
position  it  appears  as  a  square,  from  another  as  an  hexagon  with 
three  lines  from  alternate  vertices  to  the  center.  It  may  also  ap- 
pear in  irregular  shapes,  with  varying  lengths  of  edges  and  differ- 
ent angles.  We  further  observe  that  these  shapes  change  as  we 
change  our  position  relative  to  the  object  under  observation.  Now 
we  might  formulate  a  set  of  laws  which  would  tell  us  how  this  plane 
figure  alters  its  size  and  shape  as  we  observe  it  from  different 
distances  and  directions,  but  they  would  appear  rather  compli- 
cated and  arbitrary.  Equations  (5)  and  (6)  are  laws  so  formu- 
lated. However,  with  a  certain  amount  of  mathematical  insight, 
we  might  postulate  a  three-dimensional  object  which  is  invariant 
to  the  transformations  caused  by  observing  it  from  different  direc- 
tions, namely  the  cube,  and  say  that  the  variety  of  plane  figures  we 
see  are  views  of  this  invariant  object  from  different  directions. 
Equations  (5)  and  (6)  say  just  this,  except  that  the  four-dimen- 


RELATIVITY,  OLD  AND  NEW  205 

sional  space-time  in  which  we  view  the  phenomena  from  different 
angles,  depending  on  our  velocity  relative  to  the  phenomena,  is  not 
Euclidean.  It  is  homaloidal,  and  may  be  made  to  correspond  to  a 
Euclidean  space  of  four  dimensions  by  substituting  for  time  a  vari- 
able proportional  to  it,  but  whose  square  is  negative.  In  mathe- 
matical analysis  such  a  variable  is  technically  termed  "imaginary," 
and  the  use  of  "imaginary"  in  this  sense  is  responsible  for  Mr. 
Turner's  statement  that  "...  the  'four-dimensional  world  of 
Minkowski'  is  not  a  universe  which  is  more  truly  real  than  the 
spaciotemporal  world  of  perceptual  experience."  The  use  of  the 
"imaginary"  in  this  connection  is  entirely  unnecessary,  and  is 
indeed  only  a  mathematical  artifice  to  simplify  certain  aspects  of 
the  theory,  just  as  certain  vectors  are  represented  by  complex  num- 
bers which  have  an  "imaginary"  part,  in  computations  involving 
alternating  currents.  We  may  say  that  Minkowski 's  world  is  Eu- 
clidean and  four-dimensional,  but  that  our  sense  of  perception  of 
the  fourth  dimension  as  time  can  not  perceive  it  in  kind  with  the 
other  three  dimensions,  but  must  perceive  a  different  function  of 
it,  i.e.,  -^-lu,  where  "u"  is  in  kind  with  the  three  spacial 
dimensions,  or  we  may  say  that  we  perceive  all  four  dimensions  as 
similar  in  kind,  and  that  Minkowski 's  world  is  non-Euclidean.  In 
either  case  the  percept-concept  is  non-Euclidean,  and  the  argument 
has  the  metaphysical  possibilities  of  the  question  as  to  whether 
we  are  looking  up  if  we  are  standing  on  our  heads  and  looking 
down.  The  four-dimensional  world  is  more  real  than  the  spatial 
world  of  three  dimensions  in  exactly  the  same  sense  that  the  cube 
is  more  real  than  the  multitude  of  variously  shaped  plane  figures 
we  observe  when  looking  at  it  from  different  positions.  It  is  the 
invariant  that  we  are  compelled  to  regard  as  fundamental  in  seek- 
ing that  interpretation  of  results  which  involves  the  least  number 
of  arbitrary  assumptions.  In  the  same  sense  that  it  would  be  ex- 
ceedingly arbitrary  to  regard  the  plane  figure  which  changes  size 
and  shape  as  we  change  our  position,  as  the  fundamental  entity,  it 
is  arbitrary  to  regard  the  figures  of  spatial  points  which  change 
shape  according  to  equation  (5)  as  fundamental,  when  the  changes 
may  be  perfectly  interpreted  as  a  revolution  of  an  invariant  in 
four-dimensional  space. 

We  must,  therefore,  take  direct  issue  with  Mr.  Turner's  state- 
ment that  "These  methods  and  principles,  however,  do  not  affect 
in  the  remotest  degree  the  philosophic  problems  of  objective  real- 
ity, the  pros  and  cons  of  which  remain  what  they  were  before. 
..."  Both  scientists  and  philosophers  are  in  danger  of  falling  into 
a  pitfall  of  verbal  quibbles  when  they  attack  the  question  of  what 


206  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

is  objective.  If  by  "objective"  is  meant  an  unknowable  reality 
underlying  phenomena,  it  is  hard  to  see  how  any  physical  facts 
could  throw  light  on  tin-  question  of  such  an  objective  reality.  Ami 
if  by  "objective  reality"  is  meant  the  ordinary  perceptual  experi- 
ence of  common-sense  objects,  that  is  only  altered  by  the  Lorentz- 
FitzGerald  contraction,  and  this  would  seem  to  be  Mr.  Turner's 
position.  But  if  by  "objective"  is  meant  either  a  rationalized  ex- 
perience, or  a  world  independent  of  the  awareness  of  a  percipient 
(in  the  sense  in  which  the  neo-realists  use  independent),  such  an 
objective  reality  is  profoundly  changed  by  the  "Special  Theory  of 
Relativity";  for  it  transfers  the  question  from  the  three-dimen- 
sional world  of  spacial  points  to  the  four-dimensional  world  of 
space-time.  In  our  efforts  to  narrow  the  results  of  physical  per- 
ception to  what  appears  most  likely  to  be  connected  with  an  objec- 
tive reality,  we  postulate  that  it  must  depend  as  little  as  possible 
on  the  personality  of  the  observer  and  the  point  of  observation. 
This  certainly  gives  the  invariant  world  of  four  dimensions  a 
stronger  position  than  one  composed  of  three  dimensions  that  vary 
as  we  observe  them  under  different  conditions;  and  it  would  seem 
that  the  position  hitherto  occupied  by  the  three-dimensional  cosmos 
must  now  be  taken  by  Minkowski's  "world"  of  four  dimensions. 

Before  leaving  this  part  of  the  discussion  I  can  not  refrain  from 
voicing  an  objection  to  Mr.  Turner's  exposition  of  the  transforma- 
tions in  terms  of  sound.  The  transformations  of  the  ' '  Special  Theory 
of  Relativity"  owe  their  characteristic  significance  to  the  in  variance 
of  the  velocity  of  light  relative  to  any  observer.  Mr.  Turner's  con- 
genitally  blind  observers  could  ascertain  their  velocities  relative  to 
the  medium  which  transmits  sound,  without  difficulty,  and  could  also 
detect  the  relative  velocity  of  another  source  of  sound.  Further, 
if  we  grant  them  a  sufficient  degree  of  hyperesthesia,  they  could 
detect  the  Lorentz-FitzGerald  contraction,  but  of  course  they  would 
not  interpret  the  constant  "c"  as  the  velocity  of  light.  Indeed  it  is 
not  necessary  to  the  special  theory  of  relativity  that  the  velocity  of 
light  should  be  exactly  the  fundamental  invariant  velocity  "c." 
The  point  is  that  such  a  maximum  exists,  and  the  velocity  of  light 
is  so  close  to  it  that  we  have  as  yet  detected  no  difference.  For  the 
blind  observers  to  draw  Mr.  Turner's  conclusion  that  "what  is 
heard  is  real,  and  the  audible  differences  in  the  firing  rates  of  the 
two  guns  actual  and  ultimate,"  it  would  be  necessary  that  they  be 
congenitally  lacking  in  other  respects  than  eyesight.  Mr.  Turner's 
footnote  in  this  connection  regarding  the  in  variance  of  the  velocity 
of  light  is  analogous  to  the  introduction  of  the  Prince  of  Denmark 
as  epilogue. 


RELATIVITY,  OLD  AND  NEW  207 

To  proceed  to  the  "General  Theory  of  Kelativity,"  it  will  be 
recalled  that  the  transformation  to  a  uniformly  moving  system  made 
no  change  in  the  property  (e),  i.e.,  no  forces  were  introduced  into 
one  system  that  were  not  in  the  other,  although  the  question  "Uni- 
form relatively  to  what?"  was  avoided.  Newton  saw  the  difficulty 
and  dodged  it  by  saying  in  effect,  "Relatively  to  the  fixed  stars." 
Now  if  we  try  to  express  the  relations  between  the  two  systems  in 
such  a  manner  that  they  are  of  the  same  form  even  though  the 
systems  be  accelerated,  we  find  that  the  forces  are  not  invariant, 
and  indeed  depend  entirely  on  the  way  in  which  we  measure  the 
phenomena  in  question.  The  general  theory  states  the  character- 
istics of  a  phenomenon  relative  to  any  set  of  quantities  we  may 
choose  to  measure  it  by,  and  shows  that  the  special  theory  holds  only 
in  space  free  from  the  effects  of  gravitating  matter.  In  the  presence 
of  gravitating  matter  the  quantities  that  are  invariant  are  still 
further  reduced,  and  objective  reality  in  the  sense  in  which  three- 
dimensional  objects  have  been  regarded  as  real  becomes  still  more 
elusive.  The  four-dimensional  manifold  of  space-time  is  not  homa- 
loidal,  but  "curved,"  and  its  curvature  is  determined  by  an  operator 
called  a  tensor,  whose  value  for  any  point  is  dependent  upon  the 
distribution  of  matter.  This  curvature  must  be  regarded  as  having 
a  certain  objectivity.  By  suitably  choosing  our  conditions  of  obser- 
vation in  any  one  place,  we  can  remove  it  locally,  as  for  instance  we 
can  lose  weight  for  a  few  seconds  in  an  elevator  that  starts  to  de- 
scend, but  our  elation  is  short  lived,  or  would  be  should  we  get  on 
a  pair  of  scales  as  the  elevator  approaches  a  landing.  Removing; 
the  effect  in  one  location  augments  it  in  the  remainder  of  the  con- 
tinuum. 

Among  the  physical  concepts  formerly  considered  fundamental, 
the  only  ones  that  still  remain  invariant  are  the  concept  of  ' '  action, ' ' 
which  is  of  the  dimensions  of  energy  times  time,  and  the  thermody- 
namic  function,  "entropy."  From  the  new  standpoint,  qualities 
that  we  have  hitherto  regarded  as  theoretically  being  able  to  increase 
without  limit,  are  definitely  limited.  Thus  we  have  a  maximum 
velocity  "  c, "  and  a  definite  extent  of  space  which  may  be  computed 
as  a  function  of  the  mean  density  of  matter.  There  also  appears 
to  be  an  upper  limit  to  the  density  of  matter  or  energy.  These  re- 
sults are  due,  not  as  Mr.  Turner  says  in  concluding  "to  the  funda- 
mental role,  already  alluded  to,  played  by  light  and  vision  in  normal 
experience, ' '  but  to  the  discovery  that  there  is  a  fundamental  velocity 
that  is  invariant,  and  which  happens  to  be  very  near  the  velocity 
of  light;  so  near  in  fact  that  the  two  are  quite  generally  regarded 


208  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

as  identical.  My  reason  for  stating  it  in  this  way  is  to  emphasize 
the  point  that  is  not  the  fact  that  this  velocity  is  that  of  light,  but 
that  it  is  invariant  that  leads  to  the  theory  of  relativity. 

H.  A.  W  ADMAN. 
NEWPORT  Niws,  VA. 


AN  HISTORICAL  ANTICIPATION  OF  JOHN  FISKE'S 

THEORY  REGARDING  THE  VALUE 

OF  INFANCY 

JOHN  FISKE  is  universally  credited,  and  justly,  with  making  an 
important  contribution  to  the  theory  of  evolution.  I  refer  to 
his  theory  regarding  the  meaning  and  value  of  the  prolonged  period 
of  human  infancy  in  comparison  with  the  briefer  infancy  of  the 
lower  animals.  Without  questioning  Fiske's  independence  of  other 
sources  in  developing  his  theory,  I  would  like  to  call  attention  to  an 
obscure  essay  published  nearly  forty  years  before  Fiske's  first  book 
appeared,  an  essay  in  which  the  two  points  regarding  the  value  of 
infancy  made  by  Fiske  are  made  in  a  strikingly  parallel  manner. 

A  few  months  ago  Mr.  George  W.  Robinson,  Secretary  of  the 
Harvard  Graduate  School,  showed  me  an  old  volume  which  he  had 
found  in  a  second-hand  book-store;  and  he  called  my  attention  to 
an  essay  in  it  which,  as  he  thought,  was  similar  to  writings  by  Fiske 
many  years  later.  This  volume  is  entitled  The  Friend's  Annual;  or 
Aurora  Borealis,  It  consists  of  essays  written  by  "Members  of  the 
Society  of  Friends"  and  was  published  in  England  in  1834.  Among 
the  essays  is  one  covering  six  pages  (pp.  152-57)  entitled  "On  the 
Helpless  State  of  Infancy,"  which  is  signed  simply  with  the  initials, 
V.  F. 

The  purpose  of  V.  F.,  writing  before  the  acceptance  of  evolu- 
tionary views,  was  to  show  the  ' ' graciousness  of  Providence"  in 
establishing  the  long  period  of  helpless  human  infancy.  The  pur- 
pose of  Fiske  was  to  support  the  evolutionary  theory  by  showing 
the  significance  of  a  lengthened  infancy  as  a  factor  in  bridging 
the  gap  between  brute  and  man,  and  to  account  for  the  evolution 
of  human  intelligence  and  morals.  Indirectly,  however,  Fiske  was 
attempting  to  "justify  the  ways  of  God  to  man"  by  pointing  out 
the  goodness  of  the  Power  manifested  in  the  evolutionary  process, 
and  for  this  reason  the  similarity  between  Fiske's  theories  and 
V.  F.  's  become  all  the  more  striking.  According  to  Fiske,  as  is  well 
known,  a  long  period  of  infancy  is  valuable,  first,  in  giving  time  for 
educative  influences  to  work  upon  the  plastic  brain  and  in  making 


JOHN  FISKE'S  THEORY  OF  INFANCY  209 

possible  thereby  a  high  development  of  the  mind,  and,  second,  in 
making  necessary  a  greater  degree  of  parental  co-operation  than  is 
the  case  among  the  lower  animals  in  caring  for  the  young,  who  are 
dependent,  in  the  case  of  human  beings,  for  several  years  at  least. 
Thus,  according  to  Fiske,  a  long,  helpless  human  infancy  manifests 
its  purpose  in  the  resulting  development  of  the  domestic  virtues, 
and  in  the  general  education  of  each  new  generation  which  is  made 
possible  by  a  long  period  of  plasticity.  The  unknown  author  of  the 
essay  in  The  Friend's  Annual,  after  discussing  the  relatively  short 
infancy  of  most  forms  of  animal  life,  and  the  lack  of  any  high  degree 
of  parental  care  except  in  the  higher  forms  of  life,  turns  to  man,  and 
in  the  following  sentences  embodies  the  gist  of  both  points  made  by 
Fiske : 

"Thus  gracious  hath  Providence  been  to  man,  in  rendering  the 
ties  of  parental  and  filial  affection  so  much  more  permanent  in  this 
His  noblest  work,  than  in  any  of  His  inferior  creatures.  And  this 
is,  in  itself,  a  sufficient  answer  to  the  objections  and  complaints  of 
those  ancient  and  modern  philosophers  (Pliny  and  Buff  on),  who 
have  delighted  to  vilify  human  nature,  on  account  of  the  helpless 
condition  of  man  in  his  state  of  infancy  and  childhood. ;  because  this 
very  helplessness,  by  demanding  the  constant  and  long-continued 
attention  of  parents,  gives  rise  to,  and  renders  habitual,  the  tender 
charities  of  domestic  and  social  life"  (pp.  154-55). 

"This  helpless  condition,  then,  in  which  it  hath  pleased  our 
Maker  that  we  should  be  introduced  in  the  present  state,  exhibits 
many  marks  of  benevolent  and  wise  design.  ...  It  ought  to  be 
regarded  with  thankfulness,  as  necessary  to  the  formation  of  that 
strong  and  durable  affection  between  parent  and  child,  which  is  one 
distinguishing  feature  of  the  human  race,  and  a  mark  of  its  superior 
character"  (p.  157). 

"But  this  is  also  a  beneficial  and  wise  appointment  in  another 
important  respect.  It  is  admirably  adapted  to  the  circumstances 
of  man,  considered  as  a  rational  and  moral  being,  designed  to  be 
trained  to  usefulness  in  the  present  life,  and  to  the  cultivation  of 
those  religious  and  virtuous  habits,  by  which  he  is  to  be  fitted  for 
another.  It  is  necessary  to  such  a  being,  that  maturity  of  under- 
standing and  bodily  strength  should  be  gradually  acquired,  by  the 
slow  development  of  his  corporeal  and  mental  faculties"  (p.  155). 

In  the  writings  of  Fiske  there  are  to  be  found  ideas  which  are 
strikingly  similar  to  portions  of  V.  F.'s  essay.  For  example,  com- 
pare with  the  last  part  of  the  first  paragraph  quoted  above  from 
V.  F.  the  following  from  Fiske  (Excursions  of  an  Evolutionist, 
p.  316)  :  "Infancy  extending  over  several  years  must  have  tended 


210  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

gradually  to  strengthen  the  relationship  of  the  children  to  the 
mother,  and  eventually  to  both  parents,  and  thus  gives  rise  to  the 
permanent  organization  of  the  family." 

It  does  not  seem  likely  that  the  circulation  of  The  Friend's  An- 
nual was  wide  or  that  a  copy  was  ever  seen  by  Fiske.  I  have  been 
unable  to  find  another  copy  than  the  one  in  Mr.  Robinson's  pos- 
session. The  obvious  similarity  of  thought  and  expression  simply 
shows  how  hard  it  is  to  be  wholly  original  in  the  sense  of  thinking 
and  saying  what  no  one  ever  thought  or  said  before. 

WESLEY  RAYMOND  WELLS. 

LAKE  FOREST  COLLEGE. 


THE  TWENTY-FIRST  ANNUAL  MEETING  OF  THE  AMERI- 
CAN PHILOSOPHICAL  ASSOCIATION— EASTERN 
DIVISION 

rriHERE  are  two  kinds  of  people  who  attend  philosophical  meet- 
J-  ings :  those  who  go  because  of  the  papers  to  be  presented ; 
and  those  who  go  in  spite  of  them.  Probably  by  temperament, 
training  or  moral  convictions  most  American  philosophers  belong 
consistently  to  one  or  the  other  of  the  two  classes.  Probably  most 
of  them,  that  is,  are  impervious  alike  to  disillusionment  and  to 
agreeable  surprise,  and  so  continue  either  to  regard  the  programme 
prepared  by  the  executive  committee  as  the  Mecca  of  the  annual 
pilgrimage;  or  to  deplore  it  is  a  necessary  evil — something  by  no 
means  warranting  the  expenditure  of  railroad  fare.  But  undoubt- 
edly there  is  always  also  a  small  minority  capable  of  the  human 
grace  of  change  of  heart.  A  few  pessimists  turn  optimistic;  a 
few  optimists  arrive  at  the  delayed  and  gloomy  conclusion  that 
philosophy  in  America  has  gone  to  the  dogs. 

If  many  were  moved  to  unwonted  enthusiasm  over  this  year's 
oblation  to  the  spirit  of  Philosophy,  confirmed  cynics  will  prob- 
ably insinuate  that  the  fact  may  be  explained  as  due  to  the  un- 
precedented brevity  of  the  ceremony.  After  all,  nobody  minds 
even  extreme  twinges  of  boredom  or  of  pain  provided  they  be  brief 
enough;  and  to  be  served  with  but  three  formal  sessions,  duly 
punctuated  by  unusually  delightful  social  gatherings,  might  cre- 
ate the  illusion  of  enjoyment  merely  by  contrast  with  the  prolonged 
boredom  to  which  one  was  accustomed.  Any  defender  of  the 
Poughkeepsie  sessions  would  have  to  admit  that  they  were  brief. 
But  he  would  still  maintain  that  they  were  also  intrinsically  inter- 
esting and  important.  Presumably  the  chief  task  of  the  present 


AMERICAN  PHILOSOPHICAL  ASSOCIATION         211 

reviewer  is  to  indicate  what  there  was  about  the  twenty-first  con- 
gregation of  philosophers  to  call  for  special  praise. 

There  were  ten  papers  promised,  nine  given,  and  the  first 
ground  for  favorable  comment  on  so  limited  a  programme  was  the 
variety  of  the  interests  represented.  The  list  of  topics  dealt  with 
in  the  papers  themselves  included:  the  nature  of  religion,  the  na- 
ture of  the  good,  the  nature  of  a  physical  thing,  the  nature  of  phil- 
osophy. Subjects  as  wide  asunder  as  Kemp  Smith's  commentary  on 
Kant  and  the  superstitions  of  popular  philosophy  were  criticized; 
while  by  one  writer  the  concept  of  civilization,  by  another,  the 
concept  of  experience  was  displayed  for  analysis.  In  the  course  of 
the  discussion  attendant  upon  the  formal  presentations,  the  points 
of  view  of  absolute  idealism,  of  extreme  pragmatism,  of  moderated 
pragmatism,  of  positivism,  of  agnosticism,  and  of  several  degrees  of 
realism  were  picturesquely  exemplified.  The  papers  would  have 
possessed  some  value  if  they  had  done  no  more  than  thus  demonstrate 
the  actual  range  of  current  philosophical  opinion. 

What  might  have  been  supposed  to  rank  among  the  less  signifi- 
cant of  the  contributions  proved  one  of  the  most  brilliant — Profes- 
sor Meiklejohn's  remarks  on  Smith's  Commentary.  If  commen- 
taries themselves  savor  of  the  parasitic — subsisting,  vulture-like 
upon  the  carcasses  of  other  men's  ideas — a  commentary  upon 
a  commentary  should  be  but  the  parasite  of  a  parasite.  But, 
at  least  in  the  case  of  Professor  Meiklejohn's  acute  and  epigram- 
matic criticism,  the  double  negative  took  on  the  character  of  a 
genuine  positive.  The  paper  was  important  not  as  an  elicitor  of 
wide  and  varied  discussion — it  was  replied  to  merely  by  Professor 
Cohen — but  as  a  little  gem  of  analysis  and  exposition.  Estheti- 
cally,  it  had  the  effect  of  a  philosophical  lyric,  if  one  will  grant 
the  substitution  of  logical  for  poetical  poignancy,  and  dialectial 
cohesion  for  a  merely  emotional  unity.  By  deft  manipulation  of 
Kemp  Smith's  premises,  Professor  Meiklejohn  demonstrated  that 
Smith's  attempted  annihilation  of  Kant  came  to  naught,  reducing 
to  the  protest  that  Kant  didn't  mean  what  he  said  he  meant.  He 
denounced  in  particular  as  highly  questionable  Smith's  method  of 
arbitrarily  selecting  out  of  a  paragraph  one  set  of  Kantian  propo- 
sitions, forcibly  taken  out  of  context,  and  rejecting  as  improper 
intrusions  of  a  different  date  another  set  actually  interwoven  with 
the  first. 

Another  paper  which  fell  into  the  midst  of  relative  silence  was 
that  of  Professor  Cohen  on  Myth  and  Science  in  Popular  Philoso- 
phy. One  part  of  the  audience  agreed  so  profoundly  with  Profes- 
sor Cohen's  contentions  that  they  found  nothing  to  say  in  the  way 


212  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  criticism  or  qualification.  Another  part  experienced  such  thor- 
ough disapproval  of  the  spirit  and  ultimate  implications  of  what 
he  expressed  that  nothing  short  of  a  pitched  battle  would  have 
promised  satisfaction.  It  was  not  a  mere  sense  of  the  pres- 
ent incompleteness  and  unwarranted  dogmatism  of  science  that  Pro- 
fessor Cohen  gave  voice  to.  The  spirit  of  his  polemic  was  cynical — 
as  if  he  felt  actual  glee  in  the  weaknesses  and  deficiencies  he  dis- 
covered— and  the  intention  of  it  seemed  to  be  to  throw  in  question 
as  all  equally  childish  and  superstitious  the  best-grounded  hypoth- 
eses of  modern  thought.  It  was  as  they  concerned  the  concept 
of  evolution  that  his  comments  were  perhaps  especially  to  be  de- 
plored. 

They  were  to  be  deplored  chiefly  for  the  improper  use  to  which 
they  might  be  put,  all  the  more  dangerous  by  reason  of  his  own 
great  learning  and  ingenuity.  He  was  directing  his  attacks  against 
all  undue  certitude,  all  forms  of  superstition,  and  it  is  certainly 
not  to  be  supposed  that  he  intended  for  a  moment  to  lend  support 
to  anything  like  the  Mosaic  account  of  creation  as  an  alternative 
to  the  Darwinian.  And  yet  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  the  popular 
effect  of  any  somewhat  ambiguous  criticism  of  the  doctrine  of  nat- 
ural selection  is  always  the  lamentable  one  of  reinforcing  doubt  of 
science  from  the  standpoint  of  religion.  With  fanatics  in  the  state 
of  Kentucky  bent  on  controlling  biological  instruction  out  of  con- 
sideration for  church  dogmas,  and  with  certain  otherwise  admir- 
able New  York  papers  giving  voice  to  the  bigotry  of  those  for 
whom  the  theory  of  organic  evolution  is  an  a  priori  impossibility, 
scientific  doubts  need  to  be  couched  carefully  if  they  would  not 
mislead.  As  an  example  of  wise  caution,  the  procedure  of  Pro- 
fessor Bateson  in  his  address  on  Evolutionary  Faith  and  Modern 
Doubts  before  the  American  Association  for  the  Advancement  of 
Science  at  its  December  Meeting  in  Toronto  may  be  cited.  He  said 
at  the  close  of  his  paper:  "I  have  put  before  you  frankly  the  con- 
siderations which  have  made  us  agnostic  as  to  the  actual  mode 
and  processes  of  evolution.  When  such  confessions  are  made  the 
enemies  of  science  see  their  chance.  .  .  .  Let  us  then  proclaim  in 
precise  and  unmistakable  language  that  our  faith  in  evolution  is 
unshaken.  Every  available  line  of  argument  converges  on  this  in- 
evitable conclusion.  The  obscurantist  has  nothing  to  suggest  which 
is  worth  a  moment's  attention."  Any  one  in  the  ranks  of  science 
or  philosophy  failing  to  make  such  specific  confession  of  positive 
faith  should  take  heed  lest  he  be  unwittingly  counted  among  the 
obscurantists  rather  than  as  merely  an  exponent  of  an  esoteric 
type  of  skepticism. 


AMERICAN  PHILOSOPHICAL  ASSOCIATION         213 

The  only  other  paper  of  the  afternoon  session  with  Professor 
Cohen  was  that  of  Professor  Montague  entitled  The  Missing  Link 
in  the  Case  for  Utilitarianism.  As  always  when  problems  of  ethics 
are  introduced,  the  discussion  that  followed  was  fast  and  furious. 
The  theory  put  forward  was  that,  whereas  Mill  rightly  felt  that 
there  are  different  kinds  of  happiness,  some  being  incommensurably 
superior  to  others,  he  need  not  have  abandoned  the  utilitarian  prin- 
ciple that  happiness  is  the  sole  measure  of  good,  if  he  had  recog- 
nized dimensionalities  of  happiness.  This  concept  of  dimension- 
ality, so  Professor  Montague  contended,  while  doing  full  justice 
to  the  fact  that  no  number  of  pig  contentments  could  equal  a  So- 
cratic  contentment,  still  makes  possible  the  avoidance  of  any  other 
quality  than  happiness  in  the  hierarchy  of  goods.  The  difference, 
then,  between  a  simple  pleasure  and  virtue  would  still  remain 
quantitative,  one  being  a  good,  the  other  a  permanent  ground  for 
unlimited  further  goods.  The  discussion  was  participated  in  by 
Professors  Cohen,  Brown,  Bakewell,  Pratt,  Fullerton,  and  others. 
Some  acute  criticisms  were  offered  by  Professor  Fullerton  in  partic- 
ular, and  Professors  Cohen  and  Pratt  suggested  analogies  for  the 
elucidation  of  Professor  Montague's  theory.  It  can  not,  however, 
be  said  that  the  case  for  utilitarianism  was  finally  settled,  one  way 
or  the  other. 

In  two  other  papers  at  the  close  of  the  sessions  on  the  follow- 
ing day  the  problem  of  the  good  was  reopened,  first  by  Dr.  Stephen 
Pepper  under  the  title:  Primitive  and  Standard  Value,  and  then 
by  Dr.  C.  E.  Ayres  in  exposition  of  the  theme:  Before  Good  and 
Evil:  Civilization.  Again  there  was  animated  argument,  particu- 
larly with  regard  to  the  point  of  view  apparently  shared  by  the 
two  speakers,  that  standards  of  good  and  evil  are  quite  empirical 
affairs,  the  product  of  group  habit  and  ultimately  the  outcome  of 
instinctive  behavior.  Mr.  Ayres,  in  particular,  appeared  to  think 
that  a  kind  of  majority  vote  was  the  final  criterion  of  the  good. 
Professors  Pratt,  Montague  and  others  attacked  the  notion  that 
standards  are  devoid  of  objective  validity,  as  Mr.  Pepper  had  con- 
tended, and  Professor  Overstreet,  in  a  brief  but  very  eloquent 
speech,  set  forth  what  is  probably  the  most  defensible  view  in  the 
whole  matter :  that  the  good  is  not  an  absolute  in  the  sense  in  which 
possibly  mathematical  truth  is,  but  is  relative  to  consciousness, 
without,  however,  being  entirely  individual  and  variable.  The 
good,  that  is,  is  to  be  defined  by  reference  to  the  ideal  maximum 
development  of  human  valuation. 

There  remain  to  be  considered  the  first  four  papers  on  the  pro- 
gramme: that  by  Professor  French  on  The  Metaphysical  Value  of 


214  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


the  Religious  CoiKcimitncss;  that  by  Professor  W.  K.  Wright  on 
:ti>.ns  and  K.rfurnncc;  that  by  Professor  Sellars,  entitled 
Does  a  Physical  Thing  Possess  Attributes?  and  finally  Professor 
Creighton  's  paper  on  the  Form  of  Philosophical  Intelligibility. 
This  last  took  us  back  to  the  chief  topic  of  the  previous  annual  con- 
ference which  was  mainly  concerned  with  the  problem  of  the  nature 
and  function  of  philosophy.  Professor  Creighton  defended  the 
idealistic  standpoint  that  things  can  be  truly  known  only  in  rela- 
tion to  the  whole,  and  that  the  significant  inquiry  is  as  to  values 
rather  than  existences.  He  noted  the  two  important  points  of  dif- 
ference between  science  and  philosophy  resulting  from  these  two 
doctrines,  and  insisted  that  it  is  only  by  the  cooperation  of  imagina- 
tion with  reason  that  philosophic  knowledge  —  knowledge  of  the 
concrete  universal  —  is  made  possible. 

It  was  in  connection  with  the  discussion  of  Professor  French's 
paper,  however,  that  the  implications  of  absolute  idealism  were 
brought  out  with  most  startling  clearness  by  Professor  Creighton. 
Professor  French  had  stated  that  the  essential  core  of  the  religious 
consciousness  was  the  faith  that  the  ideal  is  real.  This  had  elicited 
from  Professor  Montague  a  violent  protest  against  the  confusion 
of  religion  and  ethics,  and  an  affirmation  of  the  essentially  unethi- 
cal consequence  of  any  religious  doctrine  to  the  effect  that  "all's 
right  with  the  world."  To  which  Professor  Creighton  responded 
that  the  ethicist  was  being  confused  with  the  reformer  —  an  indi- 
vidual to  be  tabooed  by  the  truly  ethical  and  religious.  Essenti- 
ally unethical  in  his  opinion  is  not  the  regarding  of  the  world  as 
perfect,  but  rather  the  regarding  of  it  as  anything  else  —  and  the 
consequent  striving  to  make  it  other  than  we  find  it. 

This  position  is  of  course  the  traditional  one  for  believers  in  the 
absolute,  and  there  was  nothing  really  novel  in  the  defense  of  it  nor 
yet  in  the  defense  of  its  opposite.  What  was  picturesque  and  really 
valuable  was  the  clear-cut  presentation  of  the  irreconcilable  view- 
points as  summed  up  in  the  protest  and  counter-protest  from  the 
floor.  We  are  so  pervasively  occupied  in  elaborating  the  minor 
aspects  of  our  respective  philosophies,  that  it  is  wholesome  and  re- 
freshing now  and  then  to  see  their  crucial  dogmas  baldly  exhibited. 
There  was  no  resolution  of  the  two  viewpoints  —  as  there  can  not 
be;  but  at  least  no  ambiguity  was  left  as  to  the  utter  opposition  be- 
tween them. 

Professor  Wright  dragged  into  the  arena  for  reconsideration 
the  pragmatist  coupling  of  situations  and  experience.  Though  at 
first  hotly  defending  an  orthodox  pragmatic  view  he  finally,  under 
the  goad  of  questioning,  expressed  a  tentatively  agnostic  attitude 


AMERICAN  PHILOSOPHICAL  ASSOCIATION         215 

which  would  be  quite  unobjectionable  to  many  outside  the  pragmatic 
persuasion.  A  genuinely  objective  world  of  values,  truths  and  rela- 
tions was  practically  admitted  by  him  as  logically  implied  by  the  very 
doctrine  of  pragmatism  itself. 

To  his  own  query  as  to  whether  physical  things  possess  attri- 
butes, Professor  Sellars,  disclaiming  the  possible  imputation  that 
he  spoke  for  all  critical  realists,  replied  in  the  negative.  A  lively 
debate  between  him  and  speakers  from  the  floor  followed  his  pres- 
entation of  the  view  that  what  might  be  called  structure — identi- 
cal, apparently,  with  space-time  predicates — constitutes  a  so-called 
physical  thing  as  it  is  in  itself.  Professor  Fullerton  pressed  his 
question  as  to  why  any  one  should  be  more  sure  of  the  objective 
reality  of  primary  qualities  than  of  secondary;  and  others  vari- 
ously defended,  on  the  one  hand,  a  more  radically  realistic  view 
than  that  promoted  by  Professor  Sellars,  and  on  the  other,  a  more 
agnostic  or  subjective.  The  consensus  of  opinion  seemed  to  be  that 
mere  "structural"  entities  such  as  Professor  Sellars  defended  as 
the  stuff  of  the  objective  universe,  were  as  highly  questionable 
things  as  Berkeley  had  found  "substance"  to  be. 

Of  the  brilliant  presidential  address  by  Professor  Sheldon  en- 
titled Soul  and  Matter  there  was,  of  course,  no  discussion.  If  there 
had  been  opportunity,  rather  lively  debate  might  have  been  an- 
ticipated. For  Professor  Sheldon,  after  a  telling  enumeration  of 
the  kind  of  considerations  which  lead  to  dissatisfaction  with  tradi- 
tional materialism,  proceeded  to  defend  a  doctrine  of  souls,  but 
souls  interpreted  after  an  unusual  manner.  It  was  a  creed  of  soul- 
substance  that  we  were  offered;  not,  however,  a  soul-substance  di- 
visable  and  capable  of  taking  on  varying  configurations.  The  soul, 
according  to  Professor  Sheldon,  must  be  regarded  as  possessing  at 
once  all  the  attributes  it  would  possess  as  a  material  thing  and  as 
a  psychical — in  other  words,  it  is  a  psychic  substance,  a  kind  of 
monad,  an  ultimate,  indivisible,  spiritual  unit  which  is  yet  a  genu- 
ine substance  and  in  no  wise  a  mere  form  or  force. 

The  annual  dinner  which  preceded  the  President's  address  took 
place  in  Main  Hall  of  Vassar  College  where  all  meals  were  served 
to  members  of  the  Association,  and  where  likewise  the  reception 
given  by  President  and  Mrs.  McCracken  was  held  on  the  first  even- 
ing. Very  much  was  gained  in  the  way  of  comfort  and  informality 
by  having  the  association  housed  in  one  building,  with  only  a  few 
steps  to  take  to  Rockefeller  Hall  where  the  formal  meetings  took 
place.  There  was  consequently  ample  opportunity  for  that  inti- 
mate interchange  of  ideas  which  to  many  affords  more  pleasure 
and  profit  than  does  any  amount  of  public  discussion.  Probably 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

few  if  any  permanent  conversions  from  one  philosophic  allegiance 
to  another  ever  occur  in  this  way,  but  at  least  sometimes  there  takes 
place  an  enlargement  of  vision  in  which  the  splendid  range  and 
variety  of  possible  viewpoints  becomes  manifest.  Effort  after  sym- 
pathetic envisagement  of  theories  opposed  to  one's  own  then  ceases 
to  be  distasteful,  since  truth  is  seen  to  bo  something  far  less  simple 
and  easy  than  an  affirmation  of  one  creed  or  its  bare  contradiction. 
Perhaps  this  recognition  of  a  reality  so  rich  that  it  generates  a 
multiplicity  of  doctrines  is  more  than  anything  else  the  goal  of 
philosophic  convocation. 

HELEN  HUBS  PABKHUBST. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  Principles  of  Sociology.  EDWARD  ALSWORTH  Ross.  New  York : 
The  Century  Company.  1920.  Pp.  xviii  +  708. 
In  a  letter  published  by  Professor  Ross  as  a  foreword  to  his  Sin 
and  Society  in  1907,  Theodore  Roosevelt  said:  "It  is  to  Justice 
jHolmes  that  I  owed  the  pleasure  and  profit  of  reading  your  book 
on  Social  Control.  The  Justice  spoke  of  it  to  me  as  one  of  the 
strongest  and  most  striking  presentations  of  the  subject  he  had  ever 
seen."  A  writer  to  whom  Justice  Holmes  and  Theodore  Roosevelt, 
not  to  mention  a  host  of  others,  acknowledge  their  debt  may  justly 
lay  claim  to  being  a  power  in  the  intellectual  life  of  America.  By 
all  that  large  public,  therefore,  who  have  known  Professor  Ross 
through  his  Social  Control,  Social  Psychology,  Sin  and  Society, 
Changing  America,,  not  to  mention  his  Changing  Chinese  and  South 
of  Panama,  this,  his  latest  and  most  ambitious  work,  will  be  gratefully 
received. 

The  Principles  of  Sociology  is  a  bulky  volume  of  over  seven  hun- 
dred pages  and  is  evidently  intended  to  be  the  author's  magnum 
opus.  We  are  told  that  he  was  seventeen  years  in  gathering  the 
material  through  a  first-hand  study  of  conditions  in  China,  Russia, 
South  America  and  the  United  States  while  three  and  one  half  years 
were  occupied  with  the  actual  writing  of  the  book.  The  book  shows 
those  qualities  that  made  for  the  success  of  Professor  Ross's  earlier 
works,  namely,  marvellous  Belesenheit,  a  wealth  of  interesting  illus- 
trative material  amassed  by  a  keen  and  far-traveled  observer,  a  zeal 
for  facts  combined  with  a  phobia  for  the  philosophical  and  a  style 
which  in  journalistic  vividness  hardly  attains  the  level  of  earlier 
works  such  as  Sin  and  Society. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  217 

William  James,  in  a  striking  characterization  of  Herbert  Spen- 
cer's philosophy,  calls  "his  whole  system  wooden,  as  if  knocked 
together  out  of  cracked  hemlock  boards — and  yet  the  half  of  Eng- 
land wants  to  bury  him  in  "Westminster  Abbey.  Why?  "  Because 
"the  noise  of  facts  resounds  through  all  his  chapters"  (Pragmatism, 
p.  39f.).  Ross  like  Spencer  is  factually  minded.  He  is  most  skilful, 
hi  selecting  striking,  interesting  and  apposite  illustrations.  If  bare, 
brutal,  unvarnished  facts  could  settle  all  moot  questions  Professor 
Ross  would  be  the  most  convincing  of  writers,  for  he  is  primarily 
an  eager,  earnest,  indefatigable  and  for  the  most  part  unprejudiced 
chronicler  of  social  facts  as  he  sees  them.  He  makes  small  demand 
upon  either  the  history  of  thought  or  the  implications  of  social  evolu- 
tion for  the  interpretation  of  these  facts.  Groups,  social  forces, 
class  conflicts,  social  processes  are  studied  as  they  present  themselves 
in  contemporary  society.  Professor  Ross's  "system  of  sociology," 
in  so  far  as  it  can  be  traced,  is  composed  of  generalizations  deduced 
from  present-day  and  for  the  most  part  American  society.  Facts 
are  drawn  from  the  treasure  house  of  the  past  mainly  to  illustrate  and 
support  this  pragmatic  interpretation  of  the  present.  The  result 
is  that  Professor  Ross  is  forced  to  adopt  in  many  instances  short- 
handed  not  to  say  dogmatic  solutions  of  moot  questions.  The  ab- 
sence of  any  comprehensive  principle  of  interpretation  likewise  places 
the  writer  more  or  less  at  the  mercy  of  the  welter  of  factual  details. 
This  appears  in  the  tendency  to  multiply  social  principles  and  proc- 
esses. Part  three,  which  contains  two  thirds  of  the  book,  enumer- 
ates some  thirty-odd  distinct  social  processes  which  are  discussed 
in  as  many  chapters. 

The  book  seeks  to  be  comprehensive.  Professor  Ross  tells  us  that 
his  work  contains  "a  system  of  sociology"  where  "system"  is  used  in 
the  philosophical  sense  of  "a  way  of  making  some  aspect  of  reality 
intelligible."  The  book  acquires  an  ethical  flavor  when  the  writer 
avows  "an  over-mastering  purpose  and  that  is — to  better  human 
relations."  We  detect  the  note  of  the  social  reformer  when  it  is 
claimed  that  the  book  is  "intended  to  help  people  to  arrive  at  wise 
decisions  as  to  social  policies."  The  main  object  of  the  author 
however  is  undoubtedly  to  present  a  scientific  account  of  the  facts 
of  society.  Now  all  these  phases  of  sociology  are  important  and 
naturally  enlist  the  interest  of  students.  But  from  the  point  of 
view  of  methodology  the  uncritical  intermingling  of  them  in  a 
treatise  on  sociology  can  hardly  further  the  scientific  phase  of  the 
subject.  In  any  young  and  growing  science  such  as  sociology  it  is 
easy  to  pass  from  the  role  of  scientist  to  that  of  moralist  or  of  social 
reformer  but  the  effect  is  confusing.  There  is  possibly  a  place  for 


218  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

a  comprehensive  work  on  sociology  that  would  give  us  a  synthesis 
rather  than  a  fusion  of  these  points  of  view.  It  is  conceivable  that 
a  part  of  such  a  work  could  be  devoted  to  the  critical  and  scientific 
presentation  of  the  facts,  another  to  the  theoretical  interpretation 
of  these  facts  either  from  the  metaphysical  or  the  ethical  point  of 
view,  and  still  another  to  suggestions  for  the  social  reformer  as  to 
the  effective  combination  of  fact  and  ideal  in  programmes  for  social 
betterment.  But  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  sociology  is  ever  to  become 
a  science  without  keeping  clearly  in  mind  the  differences  between 
these  phases  of  the  subject. 

Professor  Ross's  comprehensive  and  suggestive  book  is  a  fusion 
rather  than  a  synthesis  of  social  fact,  social  theory  and  social 
reform.  The  result  is  that  strict  justice  is  hardly  done  in  the  book 
to  either  one  of  these  phases  of  the  subject.  Let  us  consider  for  a 
moment  Ross's  place  in  and  his  contribution  to  social  theory.  This 
book  is  the  culmination  of  years  of  study,  embodying  the  mature 
conclusions  of  a  scholar  of  encyclopedic  learning  and  wide  experience, 
yet  it  adds  little  or  nothing  to  the  theory  of  society  though  claiming 
to  be  "a  system  of  sociology."  There  are  to  be  sure  abundant 
evidences  that  Professor  Ross  has  in  the  background  of  his  thought, 
though  implicit  and  fragmentary,  the  makings  of  a  philosophy  of 
society.  But  this  "system"  contains  little  not  found  in  his  contempo- 
raries or  predecessors.  For  Ross,  together  with  the  majority  of  Amer- 
ican sociologists,  leans  towards  a  voluntaristic  conception  of  society  as 
opposed  to  the  intellectualism  of  Comte  and  the  biological  material- 
ism of  Spencer.  To  be  sure  earlier  writers  such  as  Ward  and  Gid- 
dings  were  profoundly  influenced  by  Spencer  but  drew  away  from 
him  towards  a  more  voluntaristic  point  of  view.  Ward,  who  was  the 
dean  of  American  sociologists,  broke  with  Spencer  when  he  insisted 
that  the  state,  which  to  Spencer  was  anathema,  is  the  brain  of  society 
and  conceived  of  sociology  as  the  science  dealing  primarily  with  the 
evolution  of  the  social  will.  For  Giddings  society  is  not,  as  Spencer 
asserted,  an  organism  but  an  organization  of  a  number  of  individuals 
who  by  virtue  of  their  "like-mindedness"  embody  a  common  will. 
But  neither  Ward  nor  Giddings  quite  emancipated  themselves  from 
Spencer's  influence.  Ward,  who  brought  to  sociology  the  training 
and  mental  attitude  of  the  paleobotanist,  found  "almost  as  many 
parallels  between  social  and  chemical  processes  as  there  are  between 
sociology  and  biology"  (Pure  Sociology,  p.  71),  while  Giddings  was 
wedded  to  the  materialistic  monism  of  Spencer.  "All  social  energy" 
he  tells  us,  "is  transmuted  physical  energy  .  .  .  the  original  causes 
of  social  evolution  are  the  processes  of  physical  equilibration  which 
are  seen  in  the  integration  of  matter  and  the  dissipation  of  motion" 


BOOK  REVIEWS  219 

(Giddings,  Principles  of  Sociology,  pp.  363f.).  A  decided  impetus 
towards  a  more  psychological  and  voluntaristic  conception  of  society 
was  given  by  Professor  Small  with  his  doctrine  of  interests  suggested 
by  Ratzenhofer.  To  resolve  all  social  forces  back  into  interests,  as 
does  Small,  to  find  in  interests  the  clue  to  social  evolution  and  the 
key  to  social  problems  is  to  plant  sociology  firmly  upon  a  psycho- 
logical and  voluntaristic  basis.  Civilization  thus  becomes  synony- 
mous with  socialization,  culture  a  matter  of  the  disciplining  of  elemen- 
tary human  nature  rather  than  of  the  conquest  of  natural  forces.  Out 
of  these  basic  ' '  interests ' '  arise  the  social  ends  that  condition  society 
and  social  progress  becomes  a  matter  of  the  criticism,  the  evaluation 
and  the  realization  of  these  ends.  It  is  thus  a  distinct  contribution 
on  the  part  of  Professor  Small  to  have  introduced  the  idea  of  value 
into  sociology  and  in  particular  to  have  stressed  the  intimate  connec- 
tion between  sociology  and  ethics.  Small's  contribution  suffers  how- 
ever from  the  vagueness  inseparable  from  the  idea  of  interest,  a  term 
too  broad,  too  many-sided  and  too  unscientific  to  provide  a  satisfac- 
tory basis  for  the  science  of  sociology,  a  fact  which  Small  seems  to 
recognize  in  his  later  work  The  Meaning  of  Social  Science,  where 
interest  is  no  longer  emphasized. 

Professor  Ross,  with  his  facile  pen,  his  large  reading  public  and 
his  wide  learning,  is  admirably  equipped  to  give  final  formulation  to 
the  drift  of  sociological  thought  in  this  country.  He  is 
evidently  in  sympathy  with  these  voluntaristic  and  psy- 
chological tendencies  in  American  Sociology.  "The  immediate 
causes  of  social  phenomena,"  he  says,  "are  to  be  soughs 
in  human  minds  .  .  .  nothing  is  gained  by  viewing  them  as  a  mani- 
festation of  cosmic  energy"  (p.  41).  Following  McDougall,  he 
finds  that  the  instincts  "are  the  mental  forces  which  maintain  and 
shape  all  the  life  of  individuals  and  of  societies"  (p.  42).  The 
instincts  or  "original  social  forces"  give  rise  to  "derivative  social 
forces"  or  "interests."  We  look  in  vain  in  the  work  however  for 
an  elaboration  of  these  suggestions  into  anything  bearing  a  re- 
semblance to  a  philosophy  of  society,  nor  do  we  find  such  a  system 
in  Ross's  other  works.  In  the  discussion  of  the  genesis  of  society 
(ch.  ix),  for  example,  we  would  expect  some  attempt  to  point  out 
the  relation  of  the  social  forces  of  instinct  and  interest  to  the  dif- 
ferentiation of  the  social  process  into  groups.  (Professor  Ell  wood 
has  done  this  in  suggestive  fashion  in  his  Sociology  in  its  Psycho- 
logcal  Aspects,  Ch.  VII,  "The  Origin  of  Society").  This  Ross 
does  not  attempt  and  thus  leaves  us  without  any  adequate  explana- 
tion of  the  why  or  the  how  of  the  vast  proliferations  that  have 
characterized  the  social  process  from  its  very  inception.  Owing  to 


220  JOURNAL  OF  PUlLOSOPll  Y 

this  distrust  of  the  speculative  and  theoretical  and  in  spite  of  the 
imposing  array  of  terms  and  principles  to  describe  social  phenom- 
ena the  book  often  gives  the  impression  that  we  are  still  dealing 
with  the  impulses,  contacts  and  interests  of  individuals.  The  writer 
fails  to  impress  upon  the  reader  that  there  is  a  social  as  opposed 
to  an  individual  reality,  as  is  done  so  skilfully  in  the  works  of 
Cooley.  Even  in  the  last  part,  devoted  to  "sociological  principles," 
these  principles  are  merely  generalizations  drawn  from  the  facts. 
There  is  little  attempt  to  relate  these  principles  to  each  other  or 
to  a  general  voluntaristic  point  of  view.  The  discussion  of  "Antici- 
pation" (ch.  44),  for  example,  a  characterization  of  the  growing 
purposefulness  of  society,  is  obviously  related  to  the  teleological 
implications  of  the  basic  social  forces  of  instinct  and  interest  and 
yet  no  attempt  is  made  to  indicate  this  relation.  The  last  principle 
of  "Balance"  (ch.  47),  defined  as  follows:  "In  the  guidance  of 
society  each  social  element  should  share  according  to  the  intelli- 
gence and  public  spirit  of  its  members  and  none  should  dominate" 
(p.  693),  is  a  meaningless  truism  without  further  light  as  to  our 
ideal  of  what  society  should  be.  This  unwillingness  to  think  things 
through  even  at  the  risk  of  landing  in  philosophy  makes  the  book 
often  tedious  reading  in  spite  of  its  wealth  of  concrete  and  piquant 
details. 

Ross's  Principles  of  Sociology  will  hardly  take  its  place  as  a 
permanent  contribution  to  social  theory,  it  will  hardly  be  in  de- 
mand as  a  compendium  of  social  facts  scientifically  arranged  nor 
yet  as  a  handbook  for  the  reformer,  though  philosopher,  scientist 
and  reformer  may  find  here  both  information  and  inspiration.  The 
book  will  be  prized  for  its  wealth  of  information,  its  suggestive  in- 
sights into  phases  of  social  reality  and  its  vivid  style.  It  is  a  ques- 
tion, however,  whether  Professor  Ross's  fame  will  not  be  furthered 
less  by  this  bulky  volume  than  by  his  earlier  more  incisive  if  less 
ambitious  writings  such  as  Social  Control,  Sin  and  Society  and 
Changing  America.  It  may  be  that  his  most  lasting  contribution 
will  not  be  as  a  social  philosopher  but  rather  as  the  brilliant  ana- 
lyst of  a  changing  world  order  and  the  fearless  castigator  of  our 
modern  high-power  sinners. 

JOHN  M.  MECKLIN. 

DARTMOUTH  COLLEGE. 

General  Principle  of  Relativity:  H.  W.  GARB.  London:  Macmillan 
&Co.  1920. 

Space  and  Time  in  Contemporary  Physics:  MORITZ  SCHLICK.  Trans- 
lated by  H.  L.  Brose.  Oxford  University  Press.  1920. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  221 

On  Gravitation  and  Relativity:  R.  A.  SAMPSON.  (The  Halley  Lec- 
ture.) Oxford  University  Press.  1920. 

Carr  states  in  his  preface  that  he  deals  only  with  the  philosophical 
and  historical  aspects  of  the  principle  of  relativity  (the  main  ideas 
were  developed  in  a  course  of  lectures  on  "Historical  Theories  of 
Space,  Time  and  Movement,"  delivered  at  King's  College  in  the  spring 
of  1920)  ;  but  in  fact,  as  one  reads  the  book,  one  finds  that  a  large 
proportion  of  it  is  actually  devoted  to  an  exposition,  of  course  in 
popular  language,  of  the  mathematical  and  physical  aspects  of  the 
Einstein  theory,  mainly  the  special  theory  of  relativity. 

This  exposition  is  well  written,  but  it  will  hardly  make  the  theory 
clear  to  a  reader  who  is  not  already  familiar  with  it ;  and  a  number 
of  actual  misstatements  can  be  pointed  out.  On  page  35  it  is  stated 
that  "in  an  infinite  series  no  two  members  are  next  one  another, 
for  between  any  two  there  is  always  another."  This  is  stated  as  a 
general  proposition  and  of  course  is  not  true;  some  infinite  sets 
have  next  members  like  the  series  of  integers.  Others  do  not  enjoy 
this  property  like  the  continuum  of  points  of  a  line. 

On  page  138  the  author  is  evidently  confused  by  the  concept  of 
event,  since  he  talks  about  an  infinite  set  of  events  as  if  it  were  a 
single  event,  which  is  just  as  bad  as  not  differentiating  between  a 
single  point  and  a  curve. 

The  statement  on  page  77  dealing  with  the  Einstein  principle  of 
equivalence  refers  merely  to  the  trivial  fact  that  when  A  moves  to- 
ward B,  B  may  be  regarded  as  moving  toward  A;  the  true  principle 
in  fact  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  special  theory  of  relativity  but 
deals  with  the  connection  between  gravitation  fields  and  acceleration 
fields. 

The  best  part  of  the  book  is  the  historical  accounts  of  "Atoms 
and  the  Voids"  in  Chapter  3  and  of  the  "Vortex  Theory"  in  Chap- 
ter 4,  precisely  the  parts  that  have  least  to  do  with  Einstein. 

The  general  theory  of  relativity  which  is  at  the  basis  of  Einstein's 
solution  of  the  problem  of  gravitation  is  hardly  touched  on  by  the 
author — in  spite  of  the  title  of  the  book.  The  concepts  of  curvilinear 
coordinates,  curvature,  and  tensor,  can  not  be  grasped  without 
a  good  deal  of  serious  mathematical  thinking,  and  without  them  it  is 
impossible  to  understand  the  Einstein  theory. 

The  last  chapter  of  Carr  is  entitled  "In  What  Sense  is  the  Uni- 
verse Infinite  ? "  It  does  not  make  clear  the  fundamental  fact  that  we 
must  distinguish  between  the  infinity  of  space  and  the  unbounded- 
ness  of  space.  This  essential  point  is  very  well  presented  in  the  ninth 
chapter  of  Schlick's  book  (a  chapter  added  to  the  second  edition). 
Another  fine  chapter  of  Schlick's  deals  with  the  "Inseparability  of 
Geometry  and  Physics  in  Experience."  On  page  73,  however,  the 


222  .KH'RNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

reader  is  left  entirely  in  th<-  dark  as  to  tin1  di>tim-tion  between  spher- 
ical and  elliptical  spaces.  If  the  reader  relys  on  etymology  or  what  he 
has  picked  up  in  elementary  college  mathematics,  he  is  bound  to 
have  an  entirely  false  impression  of  the  true  state  of  affairs  and 
Schlick's  discussion  will  not  help  him  out  of  his  difficulty.  Schlick 
goes  much  further  than  Can*  in  both  mathematics  and  physics,  but 
neither  goes  far  enough  to  reach  a  clear  statement  of  Einstein's  law  of 
gravitation. 

Sampson's  brief  lecture  is  more  interesting  for  its  classical  quo- 
tations and  sarcastic  point  of  view  than  for  the  light  it  throws  on 
Einstein. 

For  the  philosopher  who  wishes  to  get  in  closer  contact  with 
relativity,  the  reviewer  would  recommend  Einstein's  popular 
book,  Eddington's  Space,  Time  and  Oravitation,  and  Bern's  Rela- 
tivitatstheorie  Einsteins.  For  the  mathematical  reader,  who  wishes 
to  reach  the  fundamentals,  there  is  no  rival  to  Weyl's  Raum,  Zeit, 
Materie,  which  has  not  yet  been  translated  into  English.  (Weyl  and 
Eddington  have  now  been  translated  into  French,  with  valuable  ad- 
ditional material.)  The  most  interesting  exposition  of  Einstein 
written  by  a  philosopher,  is  that  contained  in  Viscount  Haldane's 
new  book,  The  Reign  of  Relativity,  his  attitude  toward  mathematics 
being  finely  expressed  as  follows: 

"What  I  have  ventured  to  say  must  be  taken  as  pretending  to 
record  no  more  than  it  does,  the  impressions  of  a  non-mathematician 
about  what  the  mathematicians  are  saying  to  each  other  when  they 
enter  the  borderland  of  philosophy  and  speak  about  it  among  them- 
selves. The  impression  is  that  of  a  stranger  in  whose  presence  they 
talk,  but  who,  although  keenly  interested  in  learning  from  them,  is 
but  imperfectly  acquainted  with  a  language  which  to  them  is  one 
of  second  nature.  They  may,  therefore,  be  gentle  with  him  if  his 
accent  seems  strange  and  his  capacity  to  do  justice  to  their  words 
appears  inadequate.  His  reason  for  listening  and  in  his  turn  making 
comments  does  not  appear  to  be  an  irrelevant  one.  They  are  in  a 
territory  that  is  occupied  in  common,  and  forbearance  on  both 
sides  is  therefore  necessary.  I  do  not  believe  that  the  fundamental 
conceptions  are  as  obscure  as  some  of  the  mathematicians  take  them 
to  be.  The  reason  they  seem  so  is  that  they  are  concerned  with  mat- 
ters which  involve  consideration  of  a  more  than  merely  mathematical 
character.  For  the  rest  I  am  not  lacking  in  admiration  for  the 
splendid  power  of  the  instruments  the  mathematicians  possess,  and 
the  wonderful  results  they  have  achieved  with  them;  instruments 
which  impress  me  not  the  less  because  it  is  beyond  my  powers  to 
wield  them."  EDWARD  KASXEB. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS         223 
JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  AMERICAN  JOURNAL  OF  PSYCHOLOGY.  October, 
1921.  The  Stimulus  Error  (pp.  449-471) :  EDWIN  G.  BORING -Re- 
cent researches  have  shown  that  the  observational  attitude  toward  the 
stimulus  may  lead  to  equivocal  correlations  of  stimulus  and  response 
that  are  unscientific.  In  the  two-point  limen  experiments  the  use 
of  introspective  data  is  advocated.  The  Illusory  Perception  of  Move- 
ment on  the  Skin  (pp.  472-489)  :  ANNA  KEELMAN  WHITCHURCH.- 
The  perception  of  cutaneous  movement  was  obtained  by  the  succes- 
sive stimulation  of  two  separate  points  with  optimum  results  for 
durations  of  150  sigma  and  an  interval  of  100  sigma.  Some  Quali- 
tative Aspects  of  Bitonal  Complexes  (pp.  490-518)  :  CARROLL  C. 
PRATT.-After  a  defining  of  smooth,  simple,  complex,  homi-sonorous- 
ness  and  other  terms  used  in  describing  bitonal  presentations,  agree- 
ment was  noted  in  the  reports  on  the  octave,  fifth,  fourth,  tritone, 
sevenths  and  seconds,  while  there  was  much  divergence  for  the  thirds 
and  sixths.  On  Arterial  Expansion  (pp.  516-518)  :  G.  N.  HARTMAN 
AND  D.  L.  McDoNOUGH.-The  combination  of  the  sphygmomanometer 
with  the  plethysmograph  appears  to  give  a  better  determination  of 
arterial  elasticity  than  does  the  present  medical  clinical  method. 
Functional  Psychology  and  Psychology  of  Act  (pp.  518-542)  :  E.  B. 
TiTCHENER.-Functional  Psychology  has  its  roots  in  the  Aristotelian 
empiricism  and  has  taken  on  color  from  many  of  the  related  sciences 
without  adopting  the  modern  conception  of  science.  Church  History 
and  Psychology  of  Religion  (pp.  543-551)  :  PIERCE  BuTLER.-Modern 
psychology,  if  it  were  more  descriptive,  could  be  of  great  service  to 
religious  history.  The  religious  genius,  his  disciples,  and  the  ad- 
herents to  the  system,  all  need  psychological  study.  Death-Psychol- 
ogy of  Historical  Personages  (pp.  552-556)  :  ARTHUR  MAcDoNALD.- 
The  fear  of  death  disappears  as  death  comes  on.  794  death-bed  ex- 
periences are  tabulated  and  described.  Minor  Studies  from  the 
Psychological  Laboratory  of  Tale  University.  An  Experiment  in 
Time  Estimation  Using  Different  Interpolations  (pp.  556-562)  : 
LLEWELLYN  T  SpENCER.-Reproduction  gives  more  accurate  results 
than  a  statement  in  terms  of  standard  unit.  Minor  Studies  from  the 
Psychological  Laboratory  of  Cornell  University.  The  Involuntary 
Response  to  Pleasantness  (pp.  563-570)  :  G.  H.  CoRWiN.-Pleasant 
stimuli  produce  relaxation  with  a  certain  degree  of  expansion  and 
pursuit  on  their  withdrawal  when  intensely  pleasant.  The  Integra- 
tion of  Punctiform  Warmth  and  Pain  (pp.  571-574)  :  R.  S.  MAL- 
aruD.-Warmth  and  pressure  may  fuse  but  this  fusion  never  gives 
the  impression  of  wetness.  Book  Reviews  (pp.  575-587)  :  Wilhelm 


224  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

\\ViiuIt.  Erlcbtcs  und  Erkanntes.  E.  B.  T.  L'amne  psychologique  : 
H.  P.  W.  Margarete  Hamburger,  Vom  Organismus  der  Sprache  und 
von  der  Sprache  des  Dichters.  Zur  Systematic  der  Sprachprobleme  : 
J.  GLEASON.  0.  Lipman,  Abziihlende  Methoden  und  ihre  Verwen- 
dung  in  <l<r  psychologischen  Statistic:  L.  B.  HOISINOTON.  Frank 
Tannenbnum.  The  Labor  Movement:  H.  G.  BISHOP.  Carveth  Read, 
The  Origin  of  Man:  W.  B.  PILLSBURY.  Charles  Pratt,  The  Psy- 
chology of  Thought  and  Feeling:  W  .B.  PILLSBURY.  Psychological 
Periodicals.  Brief  reviews  of  the  following  are  presented:  Zeit- 
schrift  fiir  Psychohgie,  Bd.  xxxiv-lxxxvii.  Archiv  fiir  die  gesam- 

Psychologie,  Bd.  xxxix-xl.  Psychological  Review,  Vol.  xxvii, 
Nos.  1-6,  Vol.  xxviii,  No.  1.  Notes.  On  the  Plan  of  the  Physiolo- 
gische  Psychologic  :  E.  B.  T.  Experimental  Psychology  in  Italy: 
E.  B.  T.  The  Psychophysiology  of  the  Condemned:  E.  B.  T.  Locarno- 

of  Insects:  E.  C.  S.    George  Trumball  Ladd:  E.  B.  T.    Index. 


Keyser,  Cassius  J.  Mathematical  Philosophy  :  A  Study  of  Fate  and 
Freedom.  Lectures  for  Educated  Laymen.  New  York:  E.  P. 
Button  &  Co.  1922.  Pp.  466. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

The  first  volume  of  a  series  of  translations  and  reprints,  to  be 
known  as  Psychology  Classics,  will  shortly  appear.  The  series  is  to 
be  edited  by  Knight  Dunlap,  and  published'  by  the  Williams  & 
Wilkins  Company  in  Baltimore.  The  first  volume,  which  is  now  in 
press,  contains  a  translation,  by  Miss  Istar  A.  Haupt,  of  Lange's 
monograph  on  The  Emotions,  with  reprintings  of  James's  article 
"What  is  an  Emotion?"  from  Mind,  and  his  chapter  on  "The  F.mo- 
tions"  from  the  Principles  of  Psychology.  In  order  to  facilitate 
the  preparation  of  future  translations  and  reprints,  the  royalti-'s 
from  these  volumes,  together  with  an  equal  amount  contributed  by 
the  Williams  &  Wilkins  Company,  will  be  deposited  with  the  Treas- 
urer of  the  Johns  Hopkins  University,  the  fund  so  constituted  to 
be  used  solely  for  the  defraying  of  clerical  and  other  necessary 
expenses  of  such  preparation.  The  editor  requests  suggestions  con- 
cerning future  volumes,  and  cooperation  in  their  production. 

Professor  William  Ernest  Hocking,  Alford  professor  of  natural 
religion,  moral  philosophy  and  civil  polity,  and  Professor  Alfred 
Marston  Tozzer,  professor  of  anthropology,  have  been  appointed  the 
professors  from  Harvard  University  for  the  second  half  of  the  year 
1922-23  under  the  exchange  agreement  between  Harvard  and  the 
Western  Colleges. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  9  APRIL  27,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  IMPLICIT  DUALITY  OF  THINKING 

TN  psychology  as  in  politics  it  often  happens  that  the  dust  of  con- 
flict obscures  the  fact  that  the  contending  parties  hold  doctrines 
in  common  which  are  more  important  than  the  points  at  which  they 
differ.  Such  is  the  case  in  the  problem  of  the  origin  of  thinking. 
All  parties  to  the  controversy  can  be  brought  to  agree  on  a  matter 
which  dwarfs  the  issue  between  them,  but  which  has  received  only 
scattering  recognition.  Whether  the  basis  of  thought  is  in  images, 
or  in  conflicting  motor  responses,  or  in  language  reactions,  the  fact 
remains  that  thinking  is  always  implicitly  dual,  and  that  this  implicit 
duality  of  thinking  ought  to  be  taken  into  account  in  every  philo- 
sophical world-view. 

I 

It  is  not  difficult  to  bring  this  out  if  one  takes  the  view  that 
thinking  is  essentially  a  process  of  relations  or  interactions  of 
images — the  class  of  images  being  not  otherwise  specified.  Every  one 
admits  that  perception  is  selective ;  I  perceive  an  object  always  in  a 
milieu,  against  a  background.  The  background,  while  I  may  pay  no 
attention  to  it  as  such,  is  the  indispensable  condition  of  my  seeing 
the  object.  If  at  any  moment  I  widen  my  field  of  vision,  I  then 
include  something  which  a  moment  ago  belonged  to  the  background ; 
but  there  is  at  the  new  moment  a  residual  or  a  new  background, 
which  is  the  condition  of  my  seeing  what  lies  within  the  new  field. 
The  point  is,  not  that  I  actually  see  the  background  at  any  moment, 
but  that  I  am  able  to  see  it ;  the  duality  is  not  explicit,  but  implicit. 
We  may  say  that  at  any  moment  I  see  an  object,  a,  by  reason  of  the 
fact  that  I  am  able  to  see  a  background,  not-a.  Professor  Sheldon 
has  mentioned  this  fact,  which  might  serve  as  a  psychological  start- 
ing-point for  a  metaphysical  discussion  of  duality.  As  he  puts  it, 

Human  attention  is  selective;  we  fix  the  eye  on  one  spot  and  the  sur- 
roundings pass  more  or  less  out  of  the  visual  field.  But  we  do  not  thereby 
deny  the  actuality  of  what  is  beyond  the  fringe  of  vision.  We  ignore  it, 
we  exclude  it  from  our  sight,  but  there  is  objectively  no  exclusion.  Here 
is  a  matter  whose  importance,  so  far  as  we  know,  philosophers  have  never 
recognized.  They  are  wont  to  justify  their  exclusive  partisanships  by  re- 

225 


226  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

f  err  ing  to  the  narrowness  of  the  field  of  attention;  but  they  altogether 
overlook  the  fact  that  this  narrowness  is  not  at  all  of  a  denying  sort,  but 
is  just  an  ignoring.  .  .  .* 

He  does  not,  however,  develop  this  into  a  psychological  approach  to 
the  problems  of  duality — a  line  of  approach  which  the  present  paper 
aims  to  explore. 

The  first  step,  according  to  the  view  we  ere  now  considering,  is 
that  from  perceptions  to  images.  It  is  not  necessary,  for  our  pur- 
poses, to  become  involved  in  the  interminable  discussions  at  this 
point — for,  if  one  admits  at  all  the  existence  of  images,  one  is 
obliged  to  admit  that  they  are  distinguished  just  as  perceptions  are 
distinguished,  in  the  midst  of  their  attending  conditions.  Every 
theory  of  attention  and  even  of  consciousness 2  implies  this  duality ; 
the  wonder  is  that  a  fact  which  is  so  plain  in  psychology  can  have 
been  so  easily  underestimated  in  logic  and  metaphysics.  If  we  say 
that  thinking  is  a  play  of  images,  we  ought  to  keep  consistently  to 
the  principle  that  every  thought-image,  a',  implies  a  possibility  of 
thinking  not-a'.  But  it  is  of  course  true  that  many  now  hold  that 
thinking  ought  to  be  described  in  other  terms  than  those  of  a  play  of 
images. 

When  one  turns  to  these  recent  writers,  it  is  not  difficult  to  see  that 
for  those  who  regard  thinking  as  the  result  of  a  hesitation  or  conflict 
between  rival  motor  responses  or  tendencies,  it  must  be  an  affair  of 
dualities.  According  to  Professor  Dewey,  "Thinking  takes  its  de- 
parture from  specific  conflicts  in  experience  that  occasion  perplexity 
and  trouble. " 8  It  should  be  noted  that  it  is  the  duality  implied  in 
this  starting-point  of  thinking  which  chiefly  concerns  us;  Dewey 
often  emphasizes  a  duality  which  from  our  present  point  of  view  is 
subordinate.  Thus  he  says, 

The  conflicting  situation  inevitably  polarizes  or  dichotomizes  itself. 
There  is  somewhat  which  is  untouched  in  the  contention  of  incompatibles. 
There  is  something  which  remains  secure,  unquestioned.  On  the  other 
hand,  there  are  elements  which  are  rendered  doubtful  and  precarious. 
This  gives  the  framework  of  the  general  distribution  of  the  field  into 
"  facts,"  the  given,  the  presented,  the  Datum ;  and  ideas,  the  ideal,  the  con- 
ceived, the  Thought.* 

Such  a  dichotomy  may  be  developed  in  each  of  the  rival  tendencies, 
in  the  course  of  the  "location  and  definition"5  of  the  "felt  diffi- 

i  Strife  of  Systems  and  Productive  Duality  (1918),  pp.  475-476. 
»  Jan*w,  Principles  of  Psychology  (1890),  VoL  I,  p.  139. 
»  Beoonttruction  in  Philosophy  (1920),  p.  138. 

*  Studies  in  Logical  Theory  (1903),  p.  50. 

•  How  We  Think  (1910),  ch.  VI. 


THE  IMPLICIT  DUALITY  OF  THINKING  227 

culty,"  or  the  "development  by  reasoning  of  the  bearings  of  the 
suggestion. ' '  But  the  fundamental  duality  is  found  in  the  fact  that 

diverse  anticipated  ends  may  provoke  divided  and  competing  present  re- 
actions; the  organism  may  be  torn  between  different  courses,  each  inter- 
fering with  the  completion  of  the  other.  This  intra-organic  pulling  and 
hauling,  this  strife  of  active  tendencies  is  a  genuine  phenomenon.6 

Thinking  thus  conies  to  be  viewed  as  a  special  case  of  the  inhibition 
of  certain  reflexes  by  other  antagonistic  reflexes. 

This  condition  of  implicit  duality  is  not  essentially  altered  if 
one  adopts  the  view  of  Professor  Watson  that  thinking  is  a  result 
of  language  habits,  although,  owing  to  later  substitutions,  it  need 
not  always  take  place  in  terms  of  words ; 7  for  language  itself  in- 
volves an  act  of  selective  attention  on  the  part  of  the  speaker,  and 
an  attempt  to  secure  an  act  of  selective  attention  on  the  part  of  a 
listener.  Its  motivation,  from  the  animal  cry  all  the  way  to  the 
most  highly  developed  type  of  discourse,  is  the  partial  or  complete 
transfer  of  a  selective  adjustment  from  one  member  of  a  group  to 
another  member  or  other  members.  In  its  developed  forms  its 
function  is  often  to  throw  the  weight  of  the  speaker's  experience 
to  one  or  another  of  the  competing  tendencies  of  the  listener. 

Articulate  language,  and  above  all  the  language  of  philosophical 
discussion,  differs  so  much  from  animal  cries  that  it  is  easy  to  lose 
sight  of  inherent  limitations  of  this  kind ;  but  detailed  consideration 
of  these  differences  shows,  we  think,  that  these  limitations  persist. 
The  first  difference  between  animal  cries  and  articulate  language  is 
in  the  fact  that  in  the  latter  parts  of  speech  have  been  developed, 
and  expression  is  in  the  form  of  more  or  less  complete  sentences. 
This  development,  in  the  sub-human  and  human  groups,  can  be 
reconstructed  with  a  good  deal  of  plausibility  if  one  pictures  a 
progressive  series  of  separations  from  the  objects  which  are  of 
interest  to  the  groups  and  the  actions  in  which  the  groups  are  en- 
gaged. For  the  animal  group,  we  may  suppose  that  the  objects  and 
actions  are  present,  and  factors  of  immediate  experience.  When 
the  objects  are  thus  present,  and  actions  upon  them  are  in  the  atten- 
tion of  every  member  of  the  group,  there  is  no  need  of  an  elaborate 
language  reaction ;  if  any  sound  at  all  is  required  to  reinforce  ges- 
tures, it  is  sufficient  to  give  the  sound  corresponding  to  that  which 
in  a  human  group  would  be  known  to  us  as  an  interjection,  a  demon- 
strative pronoun,  or  an  imperative.8  We  may  suppose,  further,  that 

«  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic  (1916),  p.  366.    Italics  mine. 
7  Behavior  (1914),  ch  X. 

s  In  this  and  the  preceding  paragraph  I  am  under  some  obligation  to  Pro- 
fessor Pierre  Janet,  whose  very  suggestive  lectures  I  heard  in  1912. 


228  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

sometimes  while  the  object  is  still  present,  attention  is  to  be  directed 
to  it  in  some  specific  way,  or  that  while  the  action  is  still  current, 
it  is  to  be  modified  without  being  terminated ;  these  situations  would 
call  forth  signs  corresponding  to  our  adjectives  and  adverbs.  Some- 
where here,  we  suppose,  is  one  of  the  differences  between  sub-human 
and  human  groups — the  latter  are  of  course  able  to  react  much  more 
easily  to  this  type  of  situation.  The  difference  is  still  more  marked 
in  the  next  type  to  be  considered,  in  which  the  object  is  absent  or 
out  of  attention,  or  the  action  has  given  place  to  some  other  action ; 
the  object  must  now  be  named,  or  the  action  specified — hence  the 
appearance  in  language  of  nouns  and  verbs.  In  some  such  way,  we 
may  suppose,  the  primitive  tendencies  which  issue  as  cries  are  ex- 
panded into  articulated  sentences.  The  sentence  is  "the  significant 
unit  of  language,"9  and  results  from  the  discharge  of  a  nervous 
reflex.  But  nothing  in  the  structure  of  a  grammatical  sentence 
does  away  with  the  original  implicit  duality.  We  may  say  that 
every  sentence  of  the  simple  types  thus  far  considered  is  spoken  as 
the  result  of  a  selective  adjustment  or  conflict  of  tendencies,  and 
has  the  effect  of  a  transfer  of  tendencies  from  a  speaker  to  a  listener. 
Language  for  us  consists  principally  of  sentences  containing  nouns, 
verbs,  adjectives  and  adverbs,  the  status  of  which  is  not  changed 
when  they  are  called  by  their  logical  names  of  terms,  relations  and 
qualities. 

Other  differences  between  the  sentences  used  by  primitive  men 
and  those  used  at  the  later  stages  of  culture  are  found  in  the  facts 
that  the  later  stages  are  marked  by  abstractions,  generalizations,  and 
the  metaphorical  use  of  terms.  An  abstraction  may  be  defined  as  the 
use  of  a  term  in  something  less  than  its  full  complement  of  qualities 
or  relations,  or  the  use  of  a  quality  or  relation  apart  from  its  term. 
Generalization  is,  as  Dewey  says,  the  positive  side  of  the  same  func- 
tion ; 10  it  is  the  use  of  a  term,  or  relation,  or  quality,  in  a  setting 
other  than  that  from  which  it  was  derived,  and  often  with  an  im- 
plicit reference  which  goes  beyond  any  setting  that  has  been  speci- 
fied. The  metaphorical  use  of  terms  involves  the  substitution  of 
one  group  of  relations  for  another  group,  often  only  remotely  re- 
sembling the  first.  All  these  processes  are  variations  in  the  use  of 
terms,  relations,  and  qualities,  but  they  do  not  affect  the  funda- 
mental conditions  by  which  terms,  relations,  and  qualities  become 
evident  to  us. 

According  to  Dewey  a  false  abstractionism  results  when  the  func- 

•  Cf.  B.  Bosaaqnet,  Logic  (1888),  VoL  I,  p.  40. 
10  Seconttruction  in  Philosophy  (1920),  p.  151. 


THE  IMPLICIT  DUALITY  OF  THINKING  229 

tion  of  the  detached  fragments  is  forgotten.11  "We  should  add  that 
a  still  more  fundamental  route  to  a  false  abstractionism  would  be  to 
forget  the  function  of  the  language  reflex  and  the  thinking1  process, 
and  that  any  attempt  to  perform  an  abstraction  which  removes  the 
content  of  our  thinking  from  the  conditions  of  implicit  duality  in 
which  it  originates  is  false  because,  regardless  of  its  content,  it  re- 
mains in  origin  and  form  still  subject  to  the  conditions  which  it 
attempts  to  deny. 

More  misleading  even  than  false  abstractions  are  the  false  general- 
izations which  often  seem,  and  sometimes  profess,  to  remove  the 
content  of  our  thinking  from  the  conditions  of  implicit  duality.  It 
is  true  that  generalizations  often  have  a  reference  which  extends 
indefinitely  beyond  the  settings  in  which  they  originate  or  are  em- 
ployed. There  may  be  no  fixed  limit  to  the  applications  of  general- 
izations about  redness,  for  example,  or  justice.  But  the  very  condi- 
tion of  generalizing  at  all  is  that  one  is  able  to  contrast  redness  with 
not-redness,  or  justice  with  not- justice;  and  the  only  thoroughly 
valid  generalizations  are  those  that  recognize  the  fundamental  im- 
portance of  such  contrasts.  It  is  by  this  recognition  that  general- 
izations like  the  law  of  contradiction  and  the  principle  of  the  implicit 
duality  of  thinking  are  able  to  save  themselves  from  the  criticism 
which  they  are  entitled  to  make  of  other  notions. 

It  is  obvious  that  the  remaining  difference,  as  above  noted,  be- 
tween primitive  and  highly  developed  language,  namely,  the  meta- 
phorical use  of  terms,  with  its  substitution  of  one  group  of  relations 
for  another,  is  a  secondary  rather  than  a  primary  process,  and  has 
to  do  with  variations  of  the  content  of  sentences  or  judgments  rather 
than  with  their  form.  "We  may  say,  then,  that  the  more  highly 
developed  language  reactions,  like  the  primitive  language  reactions, 
conform  to  the  principle  of  implicit  duality.  There  is  some  ques- 
tion as  to  whether  thinking  originates  in  language  reactions;  but 
there  is  no  question  that  much  of  our  most  significant  thinking  pro- 
ceeds in  language  forms.  The  point  for  us  is  that  whatever  portion 
of  our  thinking  takes  place  in  language  forms  may  be  regarded  as 
implicitly  dual;  and — summing  up  now  all  that  has  been  said  up 
to  this  point — that  whether  the  language  reaction  theory  or  any  other 
theory  of  the  origin  of  thinking  now  current  is  adopted,  the  same 
result  as  regards  implicit  duality  is  reached. 

II 

The  generalization  with  which  we  are  now  concerned  is  to  the 
effect  that,  if  what  is  implicit  in  them  were  made  explicit,  all  state- 

«  ma.,  p.  150. 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ments  would  be  reduced  to  the  form  "a'  as  against  not-a'."  Rec- 
ognition of  this  principle  would  modify  a  number  of  ideas  employed 
in  philosophical  discussions,  both  of  the  past  and  present;  to  some 
of  these  ideas  we  now  turn. 

The  first  point  to  notice  is  that  at  any  particular  moment  there 
are  marked  differences  between  a'  and  not-a'.  They  may  be  said  to 
be  mutually  exclusive — although  this  statement  may  have  to  be 
qualified  later,  when  more  adequate  account  is  taken  of  the  work  of 
Sheldon.13  For  our  present  purposes  it  will  suffice  to  say  that  no 
matter  how  trivial  in  content  the  term  a'  may  be,  it,  together  with 
not-a',  exhausts  the  possibilities  of  the  universe.  Sometimes  the 
contrast  between  the  two  terms  cuts  through  the  midst  of  our  ex- 
perience, as  when,  for  example,  we  say  "life"  and  "not-life,"  or 
"true"  and  "not-true."  At  other  times  the  contrast  between  the 
two  terms  marks  the  very  limits  of  knowledge — it  is  in  fact  only 
another  way  of  saying  that  our  knowledge  is  limited.  The  most 
picturesque  example  of  the  limits  of  our  knowledge  is  one  which  is 
sometimes  mentioned  in  more  or  less  popular  writings  on  astronomy, 
when  one  attempts  to  say  what  lies  outside  the  universe  which 
astronomy  investigates.  The  answer  is,  the  Beyond.  Now  of  such 
a  Beyond  we  know  nothing,  except  that  it  is  there — and  the  term 
"nothing"  is  a  synonym  for  such  "there-ness."  "Nothing"  does 
not  mean  the  absence  of  everything,  nor  even  the  absence  of  every- 
thing relevant  to  the  subject  of  interest  or  discussion ;  for  the  pres- 
ence and  relevance  of  things  not  otherwise  taken  into  account  is, 
according  to  the  principle  of  the  duality  of  thinking,  basic  and  in- 
dispensable. Another  way  of  stating  the  principle  would  be  to  say 
that  everything  is  present,  and  relevant.  Nor  is  "nothing"  es- 
sentially the  sign  of  a  substitution,18  nor  of  the  absence  of  a  sought- 
for  reality  whenever  we  find  the  presence  of  another ; 14  these  are  but 
special  cases,  in  which  the  limits  of  knowledge,  more  or  less  self- 
imposed,  are  capable  of  being  extended  at  the  next  moment.  "Noth- 
ing" is,  in  general,  whether  one  is  dealing  with  the  limits  of  thinking 
or  not,  the  term  which  denotes  that  at  any  moment  there  are  some 
conditions  which  remain,  at  least  until  the  next  moment,  unanalyzed. 
It  is  the  term  for  the  that-ness  which  at  any  moment  excludes  what- 
ness — for  external  relations  which  at  any  moment  exclude  internal 
relations.  We  may  point  to  it,  but  we  can  not  analyze  it,  nor  can 
we  discuss  it  except  in  negatives.  For  us  it  is  denotative,  and  not 
connotative. 

i»  Strife  of  Systems,  Chapters  XII  and  XIII. 

i»H.  Bergaon,  Creative  Evolution,  tr.  Mitchell  (1911),  p.  283. 

"  Ibid.,  p.  273. 


THE  IMPLICIT  DUALITY  OF  THINKING  231 

One  can  say  of  Kant,  without  intending  any  disrespect,  that 
his  Ding  an  Sich  was  the  limiting  ease  of  "nothing." 

We  can  not  understand  the  possibility  of  such  noumena,  and  whatever 
lies  beyond  the  sphere  of  phenomena  is  (to  us)  empty.  .  .  .  The  concept 
of  a  noumenon  is,  therefore,  merely  limitative  and  intended  to  keep  the 
claims  of  sensibility  within  proper  bounds ;  therefore  it  is  of  negative  use 
only.  But  it  is  not  a  mere  arbitrary  fiction,  but  closely  connected  with  the 
limitation  of  sensibility,  though  incapable  of  adding  anything  positive  to 
the  sphere  of  the  senses.  .  .  .  Our  understanding  thus  acquires  a  kind  of 
negative  extension.  ...  In  doing  this  it  immediately  proceeds  to  pre- 
scribe limits  to  itself  by  admitting  that  it  can  not  know  these  noumena 
by  means  of  the  categories  but  can  only  think  of  them  under  the  name 
of  something  unknown.1* 

And  recognition  of  the  principle  of  the  implicit  duality  of  thinking, 
with  its  contrast  of  connotative  and  denotative  knowledge,  would 
account  for  later  attempts  to  approach  the  Absolute,  the  Uncondi- 
tioned and  the  Unknowable,  although  it  would  not  necessarily  justify 
the  detailed  construction  of  such  systems.  In  particular,  as  here 
presented,  it  avoids  the  duality  of  subject  and  object. 

Of  contemporary  writers  the  one  who  is  most  at  variance  with  the 
idea  of  "nothing"  as  above  treated  is  Professor  Bradley.  Al- 
though forced,  by  what  we  should  interpret  as  the  working  of  the 
principle  of  implicit  duality  of  thinking,  to  make  a  distinction  be- 
tween truth  and  reality,  Bradley  maintains  that  in  reality  this 
duality  eventually  disappears.  Truth  differs  from  reality  in  that, 
for  the  former,  "there  remains  always  something  outside  and  other 
than  the  predicate,  so  the  predicate  may  be  called  conditional."16 
But  reality  is  not  subjected  to  any  such  outstanding  condition — for 
any  added  reality  would  be  simply  "more  of  the  same."17  "An 
outlying  field  is  here  unmeaning. ' ' 18 

Since  our  positive  knowledge  is  here  all-embracing,  it  can  rest  on  noth- 
ing external.  Outside  this  knowledge  there  is  not  so  much  as  an  empty 
space  in  which  our  impotence  could  fall.  .  .  .  The  opposite  of  reality  is 
not  privation  but  absolute  nothingness.19 

Once  more : 

It  is  senseless  to  attempt  to  go  beyond  [the  known  area  of  the  uni- 
verse] and  to  assume  fields  which  lie  outside  the  ultimate  nature  of  real- 
ity. If  there  were  any  reality  quite  beyond  our  knowledge  we  could  in 

IB  Critique  of  Pure  Season,  tr.  Midler  (1915),  pp.  208-209. 
IB  Appearance  and  Reality  (1893),  p.  544. 
"  Ibid.,  p.  536. 
isj&id.,  p.  537. 
"  Ibid.,  p.  537. 


232  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

no  sense  be  aware  of  it;  and  if  we  were  quite  ignorant  of  it  we  could 
hardly  suggest  that  our  ignorance  conceals  it  And  thus  in  the  end  what 
we  know  and  what  is  real  must  be  coextensive  and  assuredly  outside  of 
this  nothing  is  possible.20 

The  principle  of  implicit  duality  of  thinking,  if  applied  in  criticism 
of  Bradley,  would  indicate  that  there  is  a  difference  between  false  con- 
tradictions and  true  ones;  the  latter  are  those  based  upon  the  dis- 
tinction between  the  connotative  and  the  denotative  components  of 
our  knowledge.  When  this  distinction  is  recognized,  it  is  seen  that 
ignorance  is  not  at  all  inconsistent  with  awareness,  and  that  an 
"outlying  field"  is  anything  but  unmeaning.  "We  may  even  admit 
that  our  positive  knowledge  rests  upon  "nothing  external,"  but  we 
regard  this  expression  as  a  true  substantive,  and  as  the  equivalent 
of  a  "something  external"  which  is  not  otherwise  specified.  We 
should  say  that  there  may  at  any  time  be  additions  to  our  world; 
but  to  go  further,  and  say  that  they  will  be  "more  of  the  same" 
would  be  to  apply  connotative  standards  gratuitously  and  arbitrarily 
to  what  as  yet  we  know  only  denotatively. 

Of  all  the  attempts  made  to  qualify  the  realms  beyond  the  limits 
of  knowledge,  one  of  the  most  common  is  found  in  the  term  "in- 
finite." It  will  be  remembered  to  what  formidable  length  Royce 
built  up  from  Dedekind's  conception  of  the  infinite,  his  argument 
that  the  Absolute  is  self-representing.21  Sheldon  has  shown  that 
when  infinity  is  thus  taken  to  be  that  which  can  be  put  into  one-one 
correspondence  with  its  own  part, 

the  only  reason  why  the  part  has  always  enough  in  it  to  furnish  a  cor- 
respondent for  every  new  element  discovered  in  the  whole  is  that  the  part 
itself  has  an  endless  (i.e.,  infinite)  number  of  elements.  .  .  .  The  notion 
of  ...  ever  new  elements  to  draw  upon  in  order  to  eke  out  the  corre- 
spondence is  not  deduced  from  the  notion  of  correspondence.22 

Sheldon  goes  on  to  explain  the  contradiction  in  terms  of  the  indispen- 
sable duality  of  internal  and  external  relations ;  it  seems  to  us,  how- 
ever, that  discussions  of  the  infinite  which  imply  duality  may  be 
stated  more  simply  if  put  not  so  much  in  logical,  as  in  psychological 
terms.  Perhaps  the  degree  to  which  psychological  elements  persist 
in  the  term  "infinite"  is  not  always  adequately  recognized. 

From  a  psychological  standpoint  it  would  be  plain  that  an  in- 
finite regress  is  not  to  be  identified  with  regress  to  an  infinite ;  the 
first  expression  refers  essentially  to  an  effort  or  a  progress,  the 
second  to  its  completion.  But  the  infinite  is  not  the  final  term  of  a 

«o  ibid.,  p.  516. 

si  The  World  and  the  Individual,  First  Series  (1900),  p.  510  ff. 

«  Strife  of  Syttems,  p.  431. 


THE  IMPLICIT  DUALITY  OF  THINKING  233 

series ;  it  is  a  word  used  either  to  describe  the  act  of  proceeding  in  a 
series  or  to  indicate  the  fact  that  the  proceeding  has  been  abandoned 
when  it  might  have  been  continued.  When  it  is  used  to  describe  the 
act  of  proceeding  in  a  series,  it  is  synonymous  with  the  word  "in- 
definite," or  "indefinitely";  an  example  is  seen  when  the  infinite  of 
the  calculus  is  regarded  as  ' '  the  large-at-will, ' '  or  the  infinitesimal  as 
"the  small-at-will" — both  of  which  definitions  show  how  much  of 
psychology  adheres  to  mathematics  at  these  points. 

Sometimes  the  word  "infinite"  is  used  in  another  way,  so  that  it 
is  more  easily  mistaken  for  a  term ;  this  confusion  seems  to  be  involved 
in  the  work  of  Dedekind  and  the  argument  of  Royce.  What  actually 
happens  is  perhaps  more  understandable  if  stated  psychologically. 
Let  us  say  then  that  there  is  a  progress,  sustained  for  a  longer  or  a 
shorter  period,  from  one  member  of  a  series  to  the  next  in  a  given 
order,  and  so  on.  But  in  the  nature  of  the  case  such  ordered  prog- 
ress will  not  be  followed  out  forever;  sooner  or  later  one  will  have 
other  things  to  do,  or  one  will  simply  become  tired  of  the  monotonous 
repetition,  and  abandon  it.  One  indicates  that  such  an  abandonment 
has  occurred,  by  using  the  term  "infinite";  it  is  the  sign  that  one 
does  not  care  to  pursue  the  detailed  series  any  farther,  at  least  for 
the  present,  but  that  the  series  may  be  pursued  farther  if  it  is  desir- 
able later  on.  Since  the  word  "infinite"  implies  that  the  operation 
may  be  resumed,  it  is  easy  to  confuse  it,  in  a  realm  where  ' '  one  does 
not  care, ' '  with  a  term  marking  the  resumption,  or  even  the  comple- 
tion of  the  series.  To  say  that  in  the  number  series  the  whole  may  be 
put  into  one-one  correspondence  with  one  of  its  parts,  is  really  to 
say  that  two  series,  about  the  precise  extent  of  both  of  which  one 
does  not  care,  may  be  conveniently  assumed  to  be  equal  in  number  of 
terms ;  but,  in  a  realm  where  one  does  not  care,  any  number  of  other 
assumptions  are  equally  legitimate. 

In  other  words,  the  problem  of  the  infinite,  like  the  principle 
of  the  implicit  duality  of  thinking,  may  be  approached  from  the 
psychological  side;  and  when  thus  approached,  it  may  be  seen  that 
the  two  are  essentially  only  different  ways  of  stating  the  same  thing, 
or  describing  the  same  fundamental  condition.  The  finite  is  a  con- 
notative,  and  the  infinite  is  a  denotative  concept.  Anything  which  is 
a  matter  of  connotative  knowledge  we  can,  if  allowance  is  made  for 
the  imperfections  of  our  methods  and  attainments,  analyze  and 
discuss  and  develop  with  some  show  of  results ;  but  anything  which 
is  a  matter  of  denotative  knowledge  we  can  only  indicate,  or  point 
toward,  or  qualify  by  its  negative  reference  to  that  which  is  familiar 
and  near  at  hand.  This  division  of  knowledge  into  connotative  and 


234  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

denotative  might  be  turned  to  account  if  there  were  any  call  to 
multiply  the  literature  on  the  Zenonian  puzzles  or  the  Kantian  antin- 
omies. According  to  Professor  Montague,  "most  great  antinomies 
turn  on  a  situation  in  which  the  finite  as  given  in  perception  clashes 
with  the  infinite  as  demanded  by  conception";2'  we  might  modify 
this  statement  to  say  that  the  infinite  is  less  often  demanded  by  con- 
ception than  implied  by  both  perception  and  conception. 

We  may  mention  briefly  one  antinomy  which  seems  particularly 
amenable  to  treatment  in  terms  of  the  principle  of  implicit  duality — 
this  is  the  one  which  concerns  the  notions  of  beginning  and  ending. 
Beginning  and  ending  are  correlative  terms,  like  parent  and  child — 
one  always  implies  the  other.  A  beginning  of  anything  is  always  the 
ending  of  something  else,  and  vice  versa.  The  terms  are  used  to 
mark  at  any  moment  the  point  of  contact  of  our  connotative  and  our 
denotative  knowledge.  Sometimes  these  limits  are  fixed  by  the  im- 
perfections of  our  senses  or  instruments;  sometimes  they  are  fixed 
by  convenience,  or  the  interplay  of  our  interests.  There  is  a  dis- 
tinction between  our  connotative  and  our  denotative  knowledge  in 
the  fact  that  of  the  former  we  may  know  both  beginnings  and  end- 
ings; of  the  latter  we  may  know  either  beginnings  or  endings,  but 
not  both.  This  is  only  another  way  of  saying  that  our  connotative 
knowledge  is  essentially  finite  while  our  denotative  knowledge  is, 
in  the  proper  sense  of  the  term,  essentially  infinite. 

Ill 

Let  us  note  very  .briefly  some  of  the  consequences  for  logic  of  a 
view  such  as  the  foregoing.  Sheldon  has  emphasized,  from  the  point 
of  view  of  a  dualistic  system,  the  ambiguity  in  the  use  of  the  word 
"not,"  which  sometimes  means  the  relation  of  otherness  or  exclusion 
between  terms,  sometimes  the  denial  of  a  suggested  judgment.24  I 
hope  to  work  out  a  point  or  two  in  this  connection  in  a  later  paper. 
The  chief  point  to  be  noted  now  is  that  the  law  of  contradiction 
ought  to  be  stated  in  terms  of  exclusion  as  well  as  of  denial,  and 
ought  to  be  stated  positively  as  well  as  negatively.  We  should  say 
not  merely,  "It  is  impossible  for  the  same  thing  both  to  be  a,  and 
not  to  be  a,"  or  "a  is  not  not-o,"  but  also,  "a  is  known  to  be  a"— or 
even,  "a  is  a" — "by  reason  of  its  exclusion  of  not-a." 

Another  consequence  for  logic  follows  from  the  fundamental 
relativism  of  the  dualistic  view.  It  is  that  any  so-called  logical 
universal  has  an  essentially  limited  reference,  and  that,  strictly 

»  The  Antinomy  and  its  Implications  for  Logical  Theory,  in  Studies  in  the 
History  of  Ideas  (1918),  p.  239. 
««  Strife  of  Systems,  p.  471. 


THE  IMPLICIT  DUALITY  OF  THINKING  235 

speaking,  the  only  universals  which  are  valid  throughout  the  whole 
range  of  our  experience  are  those  which  allow  for  the  fact  of  duality. 

IV 

In  conclusion,  let  us  indicate  very  briefly  some  of  the  effects 
which  a  recognition  of  the  principle  of  the  implicit  duality  of  think- 
ing might  be  expected  to  exercise  upon  some  of  the  philosophies  cur- 
rent at  the  present  time.  It  is  obvious  that  recognition  of  the  prin- 
ciple would  modify  the  arguments  of  absolute  idealism  in  the 
direction  of  relativism;  there  is  one  idealistic  argument,  or  pre- 
supposition, which  we  should  expect  would  be  particularly  affected. 

This  is  the  point  which  is  perhaps  most  vital  in  absolute  ideal- 
ism— that  reality  and  experience  are  coincident.25  According  to 
the  view  here  put  forward,  this  point  might — at  least  in  a  sense — be 
granted,  but  without  leading  to  the  consequences  which  the  absolute 
idealists  draw  from  it.  In  other  words,  if  our  experience  can  be 
thought  of  as  denotative  as  well  as  connotative,  we  may  say  that 
reality  and  experience  are  coincident,  but  that  there  is  no  need  of 
going  beyond  our  experience  to  an  Absolute  experience.  One  may 
here  quote  Eoyce  against  Boyce : 

That  all  differences  rest  upon  an  underlying  unity  ...  is  the  very 
thesis  which  ...  we  are  trying  to  make  more  concrete.  ...  In  knowing 
Asia,  I,  in  some  sense,  already  know  these  other  objects.  Even  now,  I,  in 
some  sense,  mean  them  all.  Whoever  denies  this,  after  all,  by  implication, 
affirms  it.26 

The  principle  of  the  implicit  duality  of  thinking  might  be  said  to 
have  much  in  common  with  pragmatism,  because  it  provides  room, 
in  the  region  of  denotative  knowledge,  for  indefinite  growth.  That 
which  is  known  only  denotatively  is  always  at  hand  to  be  transformed 
into  that  which  is  known  connotatively — no  one  need  weep  for  more 
worlds  to  conquer.  The  principle  need  not  be  thought  of  as  intro- 
ducing a  cleft  in  reality,  for  such  a  cleft  as  it  introduces  is  constantly 
shifting,  and,  normally,  shifting  in  an  outward  direction. 
The  duality  is,  as  Sheldon  has  it,  productive,  and  creative.  It  makes 
possible  a  growing  cosmos,  and  growing  men. 

Taken  in  connection  with  neo-realism,  the  principle  of  the  implicit 
duality  of  thinking  would  help  to  emphasize  how  many  and  how 
varied  are  the  things  which  subsist,  but  to  which  nothing  in  the 
objective  world,  so  far  as  we  know,  corresponds.  Thinking  proceeds 
by  conflicts,  antagonisms,  inhibitions,  repressions;  and  the  mind  is 

*«  Cf.  Boyoe,  The  Conception  of  God  (1902),  p.  30  ff.,  and  The  Beligious 
Aspect  of  Philosophy  (1885),  p.  339. 

**The  World  and  the  Individual,  Second  Series  (1908),  pp.  56-57. 


236  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  most  marvellous  of  all  kaleidoscopes.  It  may  even  be  that  these 
subsistential  things  are  of  more  importance  than  the  term  "repres- 
sion" indicates;  they  may,  as  for  the  Freudians,  drag  the  whole  mind 
in  their  direction,  or,  as  for  Professor  Santayana,  impart  to  the 
whole  the  dimension  of  ideality. 

Any  dualistic  view  is  of  course  a  step  away  from  monism,  and 
in  the  direction  of  pluralism ;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  noticeable 
that  a  good  deal  of  so-called  pluralism  is  not  inconsistent  with  a 
fundamental  dualism. 

One  of  the  most  important  consequences  of  the  recognition  of  the 
principle  of  the  implicit  duality  of  thinking  would  be  that  it  would 
make  it  easier  than  it  has  sometimes  been  made  for  any  one  so  dis- 
posed to  point  to  the  limitations,  and,  as  one  might  go  on  to  say, 
the  insufficiency  of  ordinary  discursive  reason,  and  to  insist  that 
there  must  be  some  more  direct  way  to  reality,  which  avoids  reason 's 
implicit  contradictions.  Surely,  one  may  say,  the  contradiction  takes 
place  within  experience;  why  may  not  experience  just  as  easily  and 
just  as  naturally  reconcile  it,  or  transcend  it  ?  This  is  the  view  which 
leads  toward  intuitionism  arid  mysticism.  Professor  Bergson  has 
one  passage  which  indicates  that,  for  him,  intuition  might  perform 
such  a  function. 

Concepts  .  .  .  generally  go  together  in  couples  and  represent  two 
contraries.  There  is  hardly  any  concrete  reality  which  can  not  be  ob- 
served from  two  opposing  standpoints,  which  can  not  consequently  be  sub- 
sumed under  two  antagonistic  concepts.  Hence  a  thesis  and  an  antithe- 
sis which  we  endeavor  in  vain  to  reconcile  logically.  .  .  .  But  from  the 
object,  seized  by  intuition,  we  pass  easily  in  many  cases  to  the  two  con- 
trary concepts;  and  as  in  that  way  thesis  and  antithesis  can  be  seen  to 
spring  from  reality,  we  grasp  at  the  same  time  how  it  is  that  the  two  are 
opposed  and  how  they  are  reconciled.27 

The  most  notable  recent  writer  on  mysticism  is  Professor  Hocking, 
who  also  has  some  passages  suggesting  that  the  world  which  reason 
dichotomizes  may  be  unified  in  a  way  more  fundamental  and  ade- 
quate to  the  needs  of  life.  He  says  that  contrasts  disappear  in  wor- 
ship— the  otherness  of  God  and  man  ceases  to  be  the  whole  truth  of 
their  relationship." 

Distance  without  fusion  becomes  individualistic  and  sterile;  fusion 
without  distance  is  formless,  sentimental  and  oppressive.  We  want  our 
living  to  add  to  its  objectivity  this  unifying  consent  Consent,  and  that 
union  with  the  object  so  curiously  uncommandable  by  direct  effort,  flows 
through  and  around  all  our  deliberate  thought-work,  lifting  and  floating 

«f  An  Introduction  to  Metaphysics,  tr.  Huhne  (1912),  pp.  39-40. 
»•  The  Meaning  of  God  in  Human  Experience  (1912),  p.  343. 


THE  IMPLICIT  DUALITY  OF  THINKING  237 

it  on  the  tide  of  a  more  central  relationship  with  our  world.  Reflective 
thought,  it  appears,  is  too  purposive,  active,  self -distinguishing,  self -pre- 
serving, and  at  the  same  time  too  individual  and  unfree  in  its  result,  to 
do  justice  to  the  meaning  of  worship.29 

It  should  be  noted  that  no  one  should  expect  direct  results  from 
arguing  about  intuitionism  and  mysticism,  for  their  presupposition 
is  that  all  arguments  are  indirect.  And  one  must  expect  also,  that 
since  the  attempt  is  made  in  the  argument  to  do  justice  to  what  the 
discursive  reason  knows  only  as  the  denotative,  much  of  the  content 
of  such  indirect  arguments  as  are  forthcoming  must  be  negative  and 
even  arbitrary.  But  at  the  same  time  the  awkward  predicament 
which  embarrasses  all  anti-intellectualist  systems — that  of  being 
obliged  to  employ  the  intellect  to  formulate  and  communicate  their 
views — is  partially  relieved  by  the  principle  of  the  implicit  duality  of 
thinking,  with  its  recognition  of  denotative  knowledge,  and  its  leg- 
itimization  of  certain  contradictions. 

We  have  left  until  the  last  any  connected  view  of  the  work  of 
Sheldon,  on  which  we  have  frequently  drawn,  and  with  which  we 
have  frequently  found  ourselves  in  agreement;  the  idea  in  leaving 
the  work  until  the  last  has  been  that  in  connection  with  it  we  might 
mark  a  transition  to  a  possible  future  paper.  In  general,  Sheldon 
has  drawn  a  powerful  indictment  of  the  warring  philosophies,  and 
has,  we  think,  taken  some  very  necessary  steps  in  the  direction  of  a 
reconciliation.  Among  these  is  the  recognition  of  duality  as  a  meta- 
physical principle.  But  his  applications  and  illustrations,  it  seems 
to  us,  need  careful  scrutiny.  Any  relation  between  terms  may  be 
expressed  as  a  duality ;  but  the  duality  may  in  some  cases  be  a  better 
example  of  logic  than  of  metaphysics.  Thus,  the  relation  of  an 
object  to  its  background,80  and  a  subject  to  its  attribute,31  and  a 
mixture  and  its  constituent  parts,32  and  the  members  of  a  species  and 
their  individual  variations,33  are  all  reducible  logically  to  the  dual 
formula,  although  they  may  not  represent  the  same  metaphysical 
principle,  or  at  least  their  metaphysical  relationships  may  involve 
other  principles.  Sheldon  himself  recognizes  that  there  may  be  other 
fundamental  principles ; 3*  it  seems  to  us  that  at  least  one  such  prin- 
ciple is  that  which  Professor  Spaulding  calls  ' '  creative  synthesis, ' ' 35 
and  that  this  ought  to  be  combined  with  the  principle  of  duality,  and 

2»  Ibid.,  p.  344. 

so  Strife  of  Systems,  pp.  475-476. 

si  Ibid.,  p.  436. 

32  Ibid.,  pp.  466,  487. 

ss  Ibid.,  p.  458  ff.,  502. 

s*  Ibid.,  pp.  511,  512. 

ss  The  New  Bationalism  (1918),  p.  448. 


238  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

perhaps  one  or  two  other  principles,  in  an  organic  way,  to  yield  a 
better  metaphysics.  Admission  of  the  principle  of  creative  synthesis 
in/to  one's  metaphysics  would  make  relations  dependent  for  their 
character  as  external  or  internal  upon  the  stage  of  development 
reached — thus,  for  example,  some  at  least  of  the  external  relations 
of  atoms  might  become  internal  relations  of  molecules  into  which 
the  atoms  were  combined.  This  would  not  do  away  with  Sheldon's 
argument,  but  would  place  it  in  a  different  setting.  When  several 
such  settings  for  his  dualities  have  been  supplied,  it  may  be  that 
reality  will  not  appear  to  be  so  freely  and  arbitrarily  dual  as  he 
finds  it  to  be.  Freedom  may  be  found  to  consist  in  the  genera- 
tion of  new  things  '•  rather  than  in  the  quick  shifting  back  and  forth 
between  the  terms  of  a  duality.87  All  this,  however,  lies  beyond  the 
scope  of  the  present  paper.  It  is  mentioned  here  in  order  to  indi- 
cate what  seems  to  us  to  be  the  fact  that  duality,  especially  as  evi- 
denced to  us  in  the  implicit  duality  of  thiniking,  is  a  metaphysical 
principle  of  prime  importance,  but  does  not  by  any  means  exhaust  the 
content  of  metaphysics. 

GEORGE  P.  CONGER. 
UNIVERSITY  or  MINNESOTA. 


THE  t  OF  PHYSICS 

/•CONSIDER  the  equation  E==f(x,  y,  z,  *0)  when  f0  =  0.  This 
\*J  represents  what  may  be  called  a  snap  shot  and  is  supposed 
to  show  the  relation  of  E  to  a  frame  of  reference  x,  y,  z,  at  any 
given  instant.  But  what  does  t  =  0  mean  ?  "We  can  no  more  stop 
time  than  we  can  stop  the  revolutions  of  the  earth.  The  time  that 
we  live  is  entirely  independent  of  our  manipulation  of  t.  The  mo- 
ment we  posit  an  instant  A  in  time,  real  time  has  already  flowed  on 
past  A. 

Let  us  consider  the  room  in  which  we  exist  as  our  frame  of 
reference  x,  y,  z.  Our  position  in  this  room  can  be  defined  by  cer- 
tain lengths  LI,  L2,  Lst  relative  to  this  frame  of  reference.  Inas- 
much as  we  and  the  room  move  with  the  earth  through  space,  our 
frame  of  reference  has  a  motion  of  course  relative  to  some  other 
frame  of  reference  away  from  the  earth,  but  we  ignore  this  motion 
because  it  can  not  affect  our  actions  and  say  we  are  at  rest  in  the 
room,  meaning  thereby  only  that  there  is  no  relative  motion  be- 
tween us  and  the  room  which  constitutes  our  frame  of  reference. 

We  define  our  position   at  rest  by  giving  certain   values  to 

««  Cf.  ibid.,  p.  500. 

«  Strife  of  Syttemt,  pp.  474-476. 


THE  t  OF  PHYSICS  239 

If1}  L2,  L3,  relative  to  the  room.  Now  suppose  we  move  about  in  the 
room.  This  is  a  common  real  experience  which  we  can  get  volun- 
tarily, i.e.,  we  can  control  our  motion  in  the  room.  But  mathe- 
matically this  means  that  we  can  alter,  as  we  please,  the  values  of 
Llt  L2,  L8,  up  to  the  limits  of  the  room.  We  can  move  along  the 
axis  OX  and  then  we  can  move  back  again  to  the  point  of  depart- 
ure and  produce  the  original  values  of  Llt  L2,  La.  This  is  a  real 
fact  in  experience  and  so  the  mathematical  handling  of  Llt  L2,  L3, 
does  represent  something  real  in  experience. 

Now  in  mathematical  physics  t  is  treated  just  as  we  treat  L; 
that  is,  it  is  increased,  decreased  or  made  equal  to  zero.  But  the 
important  point  to  note,  the  basis  of  the  philosophical  error  in 
mathematical  physics,  is  that  this  method  of  handling  t  does  not 
correspond  to  anything  real  in  experience.  It  took  time  to  move 
along  OX.  When  we  retrace  our  steps  in  space  it  takes  still  more 
time ;  we  can  not  reverse  time.  When  we  moved  back  along  OX  we 
decreased  L,  but  surely  we  did  not  decrease  time.  In  experience 
we  actually  can  do  something  which  is  properly  represented  by 
saying  L  is  decreasing  to  zero,  but  we  can  never  do  anything  which 
will  allow  us  to  say  the  same  thing  of  time.  The  only  thing  we 
can  say  of  time  is  that  it  is  always  increasing  and  is  entirely  inde- 
pendent of  our  action.  This  is  a  very  important  point.  In  mathe- 
matical physics  t  is  treated  just  as  L  is  treated,  but  whereas  our 
mathematical  treatment  of  L  means  something  in  experience,  the 
same  treatment  of  t  has  no  meaning  at  all  in  experience.  The  t  of 
physics  is  not  real  time  at  all. 

A  similar  misunderstanding  arises  with  regard  to  our  mathe- 
matical treatment  of  motion.  We  say  for  instance  we  are  going  to 
describe  a  motion  from  A  to  B.  But  if  the  motion  is  from  A  to  B 
either,  (1)  it  has  stopped  at  B,  or  (2)  it  has  gone  beyond  B.  In 
the  first  case  the  motion  has  ceased  and  so  all  we  can  describe  is 
what  is  left  behind  in  existence  by  the  motion,  namely  the  space 
passed  over  by  the  motion.  In  the  second  case  nothing  we  can  say 
about  AB  can  relate  to  the  motion  because  by  the  hypothesis  the 
motion  is  not  there  but  somewhere  else,  namely  beyond  B.  What 
we  describe  in  every  case  is  space  and  not  motion.  If  we  attempt 
to  treat  motion  mathematically,  that  is  quantitatively,  if  we  cut  it 
up  into  parts,  we  really  substitute  for  the  original  motion  a  series 
of  motions  plus  a  series  of  rests,  which  is  not  the  same  thing  at  all 
as  can  be  shown  easily  as  follows.  If  we  move  across  the  room 
without  stopping  we  get  a  certain  experience.  If  we  move  across 
the  room  in  steps  of  three  feet  stopping  between  steps  we  get  an 
experience  wholly  different  qualitatively.  This  must  be  so,  other- 


240  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY 

wise  we  could  not  tell  what  we  were  doing.  But  if  we  add  the 
spaces  passed  over  by  the  steps  the  sum  will  just  equal  the  space 
passed  over  originally,  i.e.,  mathematical  treatment  applies  only  to 
space,  never  to  motion. 

Consider  another  case.  If  we  ask  you  to  describe  a  picture  but 
move  it  about  very  rapidly,  you  will  say  immediately:  "Hold  it 
still.  How  can  I  describe  it  if  you  keep  moving  it  about?"  Just 
so,  how  can  you?  But  do  you  not  see  that  a  still  time  (t  =  0)  is 
not  real  time  at  all  f 

The  trouble  is  due  to  the  fact  that  in  experience  we  get  a  per- 
cept of  real  time  due  to  memory  and  on  this  as  a  basis  we  create  an 
artificial  concept  of  time  which  we  know  as  the  t  of  physics.  It  is 
inevitable  that  in  practise  we  treat  this  symbol  t  quantitatively 
just  as  we  do  L.  This  does  not  mean  that  we  hold  t  to  be  actually 
the  same  space  as  is  represented  by  L,  but  it  does  mean  that  the  only 
possible  way  mathematics  can  treat  anything  is  the  way  it  treats 
L,  that  is  quantitatively,  and  to  this  way  we  apply  the  term  "spa- 
tial." 

The  t  of  physics  is  the  fourth  dimension  of  experience  lived  as 
real  time,  but  treated  mathematically  as  if  it  were  space.  This  is 
only  to  put  into  a  short  sentence  the  idea  that  Prof.  Bergson  has 
elucidated  so  clearly,  so  thoroughly,  and  so  beautifully  in  his  book 
Time  and  Free  Will. 

Now  in  physics  we  can  give  this  t  any  values  we  please  and 
handle  it  as  we  handle  L  in  mathematics,  but  we  must  always  re- 
member that  this  t,  while  created  originally  from  our  direct  ex- 
perience with  real  time,  is  subsequently  handled  in  a  way  that  has 
no  relation  to  real  time  at  all  since  real  time  can  not  be  increased 
or  decreased  by  us  nor  can  it  equal  zero.  These  characteristics 
apply  only  to  space.  Now  there  is  no  fault  to  be  found  at  all  in 
setting  up  a  symbol  t  to  represent  a  concept  based  upon  our  per- 
cept of  real  time.  We  have  to  do  it,  otherwise  we  could  have  no 
mathematical  physics;  only  we  must  be  very  careful  in  drawing 
conclusions  from  equations  in  which  t  exists  regarding  our  experi- 
ence in  real  time. 

All  description  is  made  upon  the  assumption  that  t  =  0  while 
we  describe,  and  hence  physics  ignores  real  time,  which,  of  course, 
never  equals  zero.  Philosophically  it  is  the  idea  of  the  absence  of 
change  during  the  description  that  is  represented  in  physics  by  fc  ; 
t0  means  that  we  are  going  to  describe  something  at  one  instant  of 
time,  but  manifestly  this  is  impossible  since  any  description  re- 
quires more  than  one  instant  of  time  to  make  it.  Why  then  does 
physics  workt  It  works  because  the  moment  we  act  upon  any  of 


THE  PARIS  PHILOSOPHICAL  CONGRESS  241 

its  description  we  necessarily  have  to  bring  back  into  the  phenom- 
enon the  real  time  which  is  missing  in  the  description,  since  we 
live  in  real  time  and  not  in  the  t  of  physics. 

A.  A.  MERRttiL. 
PASADENA,  CALIFORNIA. 

THE  PARIS  PHILOSOPHICAL  CONGRESS 

IT  was  the  writer's  great  pleasure  to  attend  the  joint  meeting  of 
members  and  friends  of  the  French,  British,  Belgian,  Italian 
and  American  Philosophical  Associations  which  was  organized  by 
the  French  Association  and  held  in  Paris  in  the  holiday  week 
of  1921. 

The  meeting  began  on  the  forenoon  of  December  27,  with  an 
address  of  welcome  by  Monsieur  Xavier  Leon,  president  of  the 
French  Association.  Professor  Brunschvicg  pronounced  a  very 
simple  and  very  eloquent  testimonial  in  honor  of  the  French  col- 
leagues who  had  died  during  the  past  seven  or  eight  years.  In  the 
afternoon  came  a  general  session  for  the  section  of  psychology  and 
metaphysics  at  which  Professor  Bergson  presided.  Mr.  Wildon 
Carr  made  a  very  interesting  and  persuasive  distinction  between 
the  old  idealism  of  Berkeley  and  the  German  tradition,  and  the 
new  idealism  represented  by  Croce  and  Gentile,  but  most  adequately 
by  Gentile.  After  an  interval  of  discussion,  Mr.  Carr  was  followed 
by  Professor  Schiller,  who  argued  that  every  fact  is  an  instance  of 
value,  and  that  science  can  not,  therefore,  ever  be  dehumanized. 
Mr.  Carr  and  Mr.  Schiller  spoke  in  English,  and  Professor  Bergson 
summarized  their  theses  in  French. 

At  six  that  afternoon  there  was  a  reception  to  the  foreign  dele- 
gates at  the  Rapprochement  Universitaire,  rooms  that  correspond 
a  little  to  an  American  faculty  club. 

Next  day,  December  28,  began  the  meetings  of  the  four  special 
sections :  logic  and  the  philosophy  of  science,  psychology  and  meta- 
physics, history  of  philosophy,  ethics  and  sociology.  These  meet- 
ings were  held  in  different  rooms  so  that  one  hearer  could  not 
possibly  listen  to  more  than  a  few  of  the  papers  presented.  I  was 
assigned  to  the  section  for  the  history  of  philosophy  and  thus  heard 
the  interesting  and  very  learned  paper  of  Monsieur  Dapreel  from 
Brussels  on  Socratisme  et  Platonisme — one  of  the  themes  proposed 
by  the  French  Association.  Professor  Dapreel's  conclusions  and 
evidence  were  to  be  published  in  book  form  by  the  end  of  1921. 
There  was  an  active  discussion,  by  Monsieur  Robin,  professor  of 
ancient  philosophy  at  the  Sorbonne,  and  Monsieur  Croiset,  who 
presided. 


242  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

In  the  afternoon  came  a  general  session  for  the  section  of  the 
history  of  philosophy,  with  a  communication  by  the  writer  on  the 
relations  of  science  to  philosophy  as  recently  conceived,  and  by 
Signore  Enriques  on  the  Kantian  theory  of  judgments  a  priori  in 
its  relation  to  the  historical  development  of  contemporary  science. 
The  address  of  Signore  Enriques  was  made  doubly  interesting  by 
the  discussions  of  Langevin,  Brunschvicg  and  Lalande. 

The  meetings  of  the  four  special  sections  were  continued  every 
forenoon  for  the  three  following  days,  and  I  regret  my  inability  to 
give  an  account  of  them.  Of  particular  interest,  however,  was  the 
Seance  generate  for  the  section  of  logic  and  philosophy  of  science 
presided  over  by  Monsieur  Painleve"  of  the  Institute.  The  topic 
was  The  More  Recent  Forms  of  the  Theory  of  Relativity.  The 
theme  was  introduced  by  Miss  Wrinch  from  England,  and  debated 
with  extraordinary  power  and  vivacity  by  Professor  Langevin  and 
Monsieur  Painleve",  Langevin  arguing  in  defense  of  the  relativity 
theory  and  Painleve"  arguing  without  compromise  against  it.  A 
more  brilliant  occasion  of  this  sort  can  hardly  be  imagined  than 
this  general  session  was. 

Later  in  the  afternoon  there  was  "tea"  for  the  delegates  in  the 
salons  of  the  Sorbonne,  offered  by  the  rector  and  his  associates  of 
the  university. 

On  Friday  afternoon  came  the  general  meeting  for  the  section 
of  Ethics  and  Sociology,  Professor  Bougie  presiding.  The  pro- 
gramme included  two  papers,  one  by  Monsieur  Clardon  on  The 
State  and  the  Nation,  and  one  by  Monsieur  Vermeil  on  Construc- 
tive Principles  and  Political  Experiences  of  Contemporary  Ger- 
many— both  of  them  themes  of  poignant  interest  to  the  French 
thinkers  of  today. 

Professor  Charles  Andler  had  been  invited  to  discuss  the  ques- 
tion of  German  methods  and  experiences,  and  his  treatment  of  the 
issues  raised  was  as  interesting  and  as  remarkable  as  such  a  discus- 
sion could  well  be.  In  this  field  of  social  and  political  philosophy 
a  visitor  felt  the  atmosphere  tense  and  sustained  in  which  opinions 
became  suddenly  exciting  and  important.  This  singularly  interest- 
ing meeting  was  continued  the  next  day. 

On  Friday  evening  came  the  banquet  offered  by  our  French 
colleagues  to  their  visitors,  and  on  Saturday  afternoon,  a  reception 
at  the  home  of  Mr.  Xavier  Le"on.  This  brought  the  official  pro- 
gramme to  a  close,  but  Monsieur  Lalande,  a  day  or  two  later,  en- 
tertained those  visitors  who  had  not  left  Paris. 

The  whole  meeting  was  superbly  organized,  and  particular 
appreciation  is  due  to  M.  Xavier  Le"on  for  his  untiring  labors.  The 


BOOK  REVIEWS  243 

Sorbonne  is  a  place  of  great  dignity  and  much  beauty,  admirably 
fitted  for  an  occasion  like  this  one.  The  hospitality  of  the  Paris 
philosophical  faculty  touched  all  of  us,  I  am  sure,  very  deeply, 
by  its  quality  and  by  its  manner — an  entire  simplicity  combined 
with  perfect  cordiality  and  dignity. 

The  discussion  from  the  floor  by  the  French  philosophers  was 
marked  by  an  amenity  together  with  an  incisive  thoroughness  rare 
to  the  not  less  friendly  but  more  lumbering  Anglo-Saxon.  The 
American  delegates  were  J.  M.  Baldwin,  W.  G.  Everett,  T. 
de  Laguna,  R.  B.  Perry  and  the  writer.  An  old  friend,  R.  F.  Alfred 
Hoernle,  was  present  as  one  of  the  English  group.  The  Americans 
presented  the  following  papers:  De  Laguna,  A  Nominalistic  Inter- 
pretation of  Truth;  Everett,  The  Content  and  Organization  of  the 
Moral  Life;  Perry,  Forms  of  Social  Unity.  Mr.  Baldwin  was  to 
have  spoken  on  the  Reality  of  Value  and  the  Value  of  Reality,  but 
he  was  unable  to  be  in  Paris.  Professor  Hoernle  spoke  on  Berkeley 
as  a  Forerunner  of  Recent  Philosophy  of  Physics. 

I  must  not  forget  the  remarkably  interesting  description  by 
Dr.  Pierre  Janet  of  a  case  he  had  been  studying  for  a  long  time. 
His  address  had  the  title  Les  deux  formes  de  la  volonte  et  de  la 
croyance  dans  un  cos  de  delire  psychastenique. 

Brief  abstracts  of  all  the  papers  had  been  printed,  and  it  is 
expected  that  the  papers  themselves  will  appear  in  a  special  num- 
ber of  the  Revue  de  Metaphysique  et  de  Morale. 

W.  T.  BUSH. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  Philosophical  Writings  of  Richard  Burthogge.     Edited  with 
introduction  and  notes  by  MARGARET  W.  LANDES.    Chicago :  Open 
Court  Publishing  Company.    1921.    Pp.  xxiv  -f-  245. 
Richard  Burthogge  is  one  of  the  group  of  interesting  minor 
writers  of  the  late  seventeenth  century,  whose  works  have  been  quite 
inaccessible  for  many  years  to  most  students  of  English  thought.    It 
is  thus  a  pleasure  to  have  his  major  philosophical  writings  made 
available  in  a  well-printed  edition.    Once  more  the  student  of  philos- 
ophy is  made  indebted  to  the  Open  Court  Publishing  Company. 

The  three  works  of  Burthogge  which  are  reprinted  in  this  new 
volume  are  Organum  Vetus  &  Novum,  or  a  Discourse  of  Reason  and 
Truth  (1678) ,  An  Essay  upon  Reason  and  the  Nature  of  Spirits,  dedi- 
cated "to  the  learned  Mr.  John  Lock"  (1694),  and  Of  the  Soul  of  the 
World,  and  of  Particular  Souls,  in  a  Letter  to  Mr.  Lock  (1699).  The 


244  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

first  and  third  of  these  works  are  printed  entire ;  the  second,  being 
tediously  long  and  in  large  part  unimportant,  has  been  abridged  and 
is  given  only  in  so  far  as  it  has  any  light  to  throw  on  Burthogge's 
epistemological  positions.  The  notes  at  the  end  of  the  volumes  are 
mostly  explanatory  of  the  literary  and  personal  allusions  in  the 
text  rather  than  critical  of  the  historical  and  philosophical  issues 
raised ;  but  they  are  based  on  careful  research  and  are  quite  accurate 
(except  where  in  note  23  Burthogge  is  inadvertently  said  to  refer  in 
1678  to  Locke  whose  work  did  not  appear  until  twelve  years  later). 
The  introduction  to  the  volume  is  the  least  satisfactory  part  of  the 
book,  not  that  it  asserts  any  unsound  thesis,  but  that  its  emphasis 
is  misleading  in  regard  to  Burthogge's  historical  relations.  The 
chief  point  in  the  introduction  consists  in  an  examination  of  certain 
ways  in  which  Burthogge  anticipated  Kant.  There  seems  to  be  no 
good  reason  for  selecting  Kant  rather  than  Sir  William  Hamilton  or 
Cousin  or  even  Herbert  Spencer.  Though  the  comparison  of  Bur- 
thogge and  Kant  holds  good,  it  is  unfortunate,  as  an  introduction  to 
this  particular  volume,  for  two  reasons.  First,  it  suggests  the  old 
discredited  method  of  treating  English  classic  philosophy  as  a  prep- 
aration for  German  thought.  Secondly,  it  also  implies  that  Bur- 
thogge was  the  only  British  writer  who  thus  anticipated  Kant,  though 
Locke  to  whom  Burthogge  was  so  closely  related  anticipated  Kant  in 
every  one  of  the  same  respects  with  one  exception.  The  chief  histori- 
cal problem  of  the  relations  of  Burthogge  and  Locke  receives  scanty 
notice. 

Of  the  Soul  of  the  World  and  of  Particular  Souls  is  largely 
concerned  with  the  fantastic  pantheistic  animism  which  Burthogge 
developed,  under  the  influence  partly  of  the  Cambridge  Platonists 
and  partly  of  Malebranche.  Its  historical  importance  seems  to  lie 
mainly  in  the  fact  that  it  illustrates  the  way  in  which  Malebranche 
was  usually  understood,  or  rather  misunderstood,  on  English  soil. 
The  numerous  English  misinterpretations  of  Malebranche  were  due  to 
the  great  difference  between  French  idealism  and  English  idealism. 
It  would  not  be  much  amiss  to  sum  up  the  difference  by  saying  that 
French  idealism  was  Platonic  and  English  idealism  was  Neo-Platonic. 
What  is  meant  by  that  characterization  is  that  French  idealism  was 
concerned  with  certain  logical  relations  and  moral  standards,  and 
English  idealism  was  concerned  with  the  proof  of  a  certain  kind  of 
spiritual  substance  or  stuff.  The  Cambridge  Platonists,  Burthogge, 
and  even  Berkeley  confused  logical  and  metaphysical  questions,  and 
endeavored  to  combat  materialism  by  establishing  a  different  kind  of 
substance  than  that  known  as  physical.  No  better  illustration  of  the 
English  inability  to  understand  French  idealism  could  be  found  than 
John  Locke's  two  essays  on  Malebranche  himself  and  upon  Norris, 


BOOK  REVIEWS  245 

the  one  real  pupil  of  Malebranche  in  England  (c/.  Locke's  Works, 
edition  of  1823,  Vol.  IX,  pp.  211-255,  and  Vol.  X,  pp.  246-259). 
Burthogge's  idealism  rejects  "the  seeing  of  all  things  in  God,"  and 
substitutes  therefor  the  being  a  fragment  of  the  world  soul. 

The  other  two  works  reprinted  in  this  volume  are  primarily 
concerned  with  Burthogge's  logical  and  epistemological  positions, 
and  are  the  ones  most  worth  reading  to-day.  The  main  historical 
problem  which  they  raise  is  the  relation  between  Burthogge  and 
Locke;  for  though  the  many  points  of  resemblance  are  easy  to  see, 
the  question  of  independence  or  indebtedness  of  one  to  the  other 
is  baffling.  It  may  be  profitable  to  list  the  points  of  resem- 
blance. In  Burthogge's  work  of  the  year  1678  the  following 
points  are  made  which  later  appear  in  Locke's  Essay:  that  "full  and 
free  assent"  such  as  Lord  Herbert's  consensus  gentium  is  no  guaran- 
tee of  truth  (36-37) ;  that  "anticipations"  such  as  the  alleged  innate 
ideas  owe  their  seeming  indubitability,  not  to  their  having  been 
divinely  planted  in  the  mind,  but  to  their  having  been  acquired  early 
in  experience  and  become  deeply  fixed  by  habit  (37-38) ;  that  to  be 
"clear  and  distinct"  is  not,  as  Descartes  supposed,  equivalent  to 
being  true  (34)  ;  that  "enthusiasm"  is  likely  to  lead  men  astray  in 
thinking  (16)  ;  that  all  the  objects  of  human  thought  have  their  locus 
only  in  the  mind  and  do  not  exist  independently  (12-13,  24-25)  ; 
that  our  notions  as  well  as  our  sense-experiences  are  real,  not  in  that 
they  mirror  the  nature  of  external  objects,  but  only  in  that  they  are 
' ' grounded ' '  in  those  external  objects  ( 17,  39 )  ;  that  truth  is  harmony, 
congruity,  or  proportion  of  things  with  each  other  as  they  exist 
in  our  minds  (40-41,  44) ;  that  faith  may  pass  beyond  but  can  not 
contradict  reason  (19) ;  that  there  are  certain  truths  which  are  self- 
evident  as  soon  as  the  mind  attends  to  them  (39)  ;  that  in  many 
affairs  the  human  mind  can  not  reach  certainty,  but  must  be  content 
with  probability  (46).  In  no  case  would  it  be  safe  to  affirm  that 
Locke  borrowed  these  positions  from  Burthogge;  for  many  of  these 
positions  were  contained  in  the  earlier  drafts  of  Locke 's  Essay  which 
go  back  as  early  as  1671,  and  others  which  were  incorporated  in  the 
second  and  fourth  editions  of  Locke's  Essay  are  discussed  in  his 
correspondence  with  Molyneux  without  the  slightest  suggestion  of 
dependence  upon  any  writings  of  other  authors.  In  the  case  of  such 
positions  as  the  relation  of  faith  and  reason,  or  the  self-evidence  of 
certain  truths,  or  even  the  dependence  of  notions  upon  sense-expe- 
rience, it  is  probable  that  Burthogge  and  Locke  were  both  influenced 
by  a  current  attitude  of  their  time;  but  it  is  difficult  to  find  any 
such  current  attitude  to  explain  other  positions  shared  by  the  two 
men.  The  historical  question  here  involved  requires  further  careful 
study;  and  though  Locke  still  may  be  considered  to  have  made  the 


246  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

most  noteworthy  statement  of  the  subjective  theory  of  knowledge, 
he  can  perhaps  no  longer  be  considered  to  be  quite  such  an  innovator 
in  philosophy. 

Burthogge's  later  work  of  1694  is  clearly  and  confessedly  de- 
pendent upon  Locke  to  whom  he  dedicated  the  essay.  The  subjec- 
tive epistemology  of  the  earlier  work  is  restated  more  in  Lockian 
fashion,  though  Burthogge  maintains  one  point  in  which  he  differed 
from  Locke,  namely  the  activity  of  the  mind  in  sensation  (76-77). 
Attempts  to  describe  the  nature  of  substance  are,  however,  made 
by  Burthogge  in  this  work,  as  by  Locke  in  the  Essay,  though  they 
were  not  made  in  the  earlier  work  of  1678  and  are  obviously  in- 
consistent with  the  epistemological  position  already  adopted.  For 
example,  the  substance  of  water  is  supposed  to  consist  in  itself 
of  "little  parts"  of  a  certain  magnitude  and  size,  figure  and  shape, 
kind  and  motion,  even  though  exact  knowledge  thereof  is  impossible 
(83-87) ;  that  is,  water  is  treated  as  an  atomist  would  treat  it,  as 
possessing  objectively  what  Locke  called  the  primary  qualities. 
Again,  two  kinds  of  substance,  matter  and  mind,  are  regarded  as 
proved  from  the  two  different  kinds  of  effects  which  they  arouse  in 
the  mind  of  one  who  perceives  them  (91).  Or  again,  Descartes 's 
resolution  of  corporeal  substance  into  "mere"  extension  is  rejected, 
and  matter  is  treated  as  a  substance  which  has  extension  as  an  attri- 
bute (96).  Still  again,  the  whole  physiological  explanation  of  sensa- 
tions as  due  to  impressions  coming  in  through  the  end-organs  from 
an  external  world  is  adopted  quite  realistically  (127).  Thus  Bur- 
thogge under  Locke's  influence  departs  from  idealism  towards  dual- 
ism, and  takes  a  stand  in  his  metaphysics  which  is  utterly  unwar- 
ranted by  his  theory  of  knowledge.  Such  influence  may  be  regarded 
as  unfortunate;  but  it  is  none  the  less  real.  No  problem  remains 
unsolved  in  connection  with  this  later  work  as  in  the  case  in  the 
relation  of  Burthogge's  earlier  work  to  Locke's  Essay. 

STERLING  P.  LAMPBECHT. 

UNIVIBSITT  or  ILLINOIS. 

Nietzsche,  sa  Vie  et  sa  Pensee:  Vol.  II.  La  Jeunesse  de  Nietzsche 
jusqu'a  la  Rupture  avec  Bayreuth.  CHARLES  ANDLER.  Paris: 
Editions  Bossard.  1921.  Pp.  469. 

It  would  be  unfair  to  readers  of  the  JOURNAL  were  a  lengthy 
delay  in  review  of  these  volumes  (Vol.  Ill  is  before  me  also)  to 
result  from  very  recent  changes  in  the  personal  plans  of  the  reviewer. 
Seeing  that  this  would  be  inevitable  were  full  review  in  question, 
and  that,  as  in  the  case  of  Volume  I  (cf.  this  JOURNAL,  Sept.  1, 
1921),  such  review  must  needs  await  completion  of  the  work,  I  sub- 
mit some  account  of  M.  Andler's  progress,  pour  servir. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  247 

Volume  II  contains  an  Introduction,  and  three  Books — the 
"Shaping  of  Nietzsche";  the  "Preparation  for  the  Book  on 
Tragedy";  the  "Attempt  to  Reform  Wagnerism."  But  these  titles 
offer  little  indication  of  the  variety  and  suggestiveness  of  the  con- 
tents. 

The  Introduction  gives  Andler  an  opportunity  to  state  his  manner 
of  approach,  and  to  issue  a  warning  about  the  two  Nietzsche  ' '  tradi- 
tions"— that  of  Wiemar  and  that  of  Basle — lions  in  the  path.  Book 
I  consists  of  two  chapters ;  on  "  Forebears  and  Adolescence, ' '  and  the 
"University  and  the  Influence  of  0.  Eitschl"  respectively.  The 
pictures  of  Saxon  culture,  of  the  Lutheran  rural  clergy  (reminding 
one  forcibly  of  Scotland),  and  of  the  unique  school  at  Pforta,  are 
admirably  drawn.  There  is  a  splendid  pen-portrait  of  Ritschl.  It 
affords  an  illuminating  clue  to  the  humanistic  German  "man  of 
science"  in  the  mid-nineteenth  century — the  zeal  of  thine  house  hath 
eaten  me  up.  Book  II  opens  with  an  equally  informing  presenta- 
tion of  social  and  cultural  conditions  at  Basle  when  Nietzsche  arrived 
upon  the  scene;  a  town  with  a  distinctive  atmosphere  of  its  own, 
like  so  many  Teutonic  centers  from  of  old — Francke  's  Halle,  Kant 's 
Koenigsberg,  Goethe's  Weimar,  Schelling's  Jena,  for  example.  Fol- 
lows a  charming  account  of  the  "Idyl  of  Tribschen" — Nietzsche  in 
the  'bosom  of  Wagner  domesticity.  Chapter  I  concludes  with  the 
events  attendant  upon  the  war  of  1870,  and  I  am  glad  to  see  that 
Andler  treats  Nietzsche's  physical  mischance  as  an  incident. 
Chapter  II  describes  Nietzsche's  intercourse  with  five  intimate 
friends — Paul  Deussen,  Heinrich  Bomundt,  Carl  von  Gersdorff, 
Erwin  Rohde,  and  Franz  Overbeck — saying  something  about  reper- 
cussions; and  stresses  the  influence  of  the  family  circle,  making 
some  pointed  remarks  on  the  sister,  now  famous,  thanks  to  the 
brother's  reflected  glory,  but  not  always  to  be  taken,  for  this  mere  ac- 
cident, an  pied  de  la  lettre.  Chapter  III  is  devoted  to  an  intensive 
account  of  the  intimate  soul-relations  between  Nietzsche  and  Wagner, 
in  which  Andler  takes  care  to  hint  (Sect,  ii)  the  subtle  part  played 
by  Cosima  Wagner,  the  "Corinne-Ariane"  of  the  Empedocles  Frag- 
ment. Some  reading  between  the  lines  is  necessary  here ;  but  section 
i  of  Chapter  V  ("The  Foundation  of  Bayreuth,"  some  70  pp.  later) 
serves  to  make  matters  plainer.  Chapter  IV  is  specially  noteworthy 
for  its  analysis  of  the  sources  of  the  Birth,  of  Tragedy — in  the  Roman- 
tics (Fr.  and  W.  Schlegel,  and  Fr.  Creuzer),  in  O.  Miiller,  Fr. 
Welcker,  J.  J.  Bachofen,  and  Fr.  Liszt.  The  summary  (pp.  272  f.) 
points  the  moral  well  (cf.  pp.  289  f.).  As  just  indicated,  chapter 
V,  concluding  Book  II,  pictures  Tribschen  at  its  warmest ;  an  exhibi- 
tion (the  most  intimative  among  not  a  few)  of  German  Schwarmerei 


248  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

nigh  incredible  to  the  phlegmatic  (and  barbarous!)  Anglo-Saxon. 
In  short,  Romanticism  rampageous,  ante-Bismarck  Kultur  in 
excelsisl 

Book  III  raises  issues  even  more  interesting.  We  see  Nietzsche 
just  beginning  to  free  himself,  and  to  sense  problems  destined  to  re- 
turn for  judgment  till  the  last.  Chapter  I  deals  with  "Nietzsche's 
First  Scientific  Studies" — not  Wissenschaft,  but  natural  science. 
The  physicists  Boscovich,  Pouillet,  and  Mohr,  the  chemists  Kopp  and 
Landenberg,  and  the  cosmologist  Maedler,  furnished  much  food  for 
thought.  But  the  main  spell  seems  to  have  been  exerted  by  J.  K.  F. 
Zollner,  the  Leipzig  astronomer,  who  attacked  his  fellow  physicists 
much  as  Nietzsche  had  attacked  his  fellow  philologists ;  and  who  met 
a  similar  reception — witness  Wilamowitz's  famous  or  infamous 
Zukunftsphilologie  (pp.  291  f.).  His  "scandalous"  'book,  tiber  die 
Natur  Kometen,  a  contribution  rather  to  the  literature  of  panpsy- 
chism  than  of  astronomy,  posed  the  question  of  the  "unconscious," 
then  clamant.  It  jumbled  the  terminology  of  physics  and  psychol- 
ogy, transforming  facts  observed  in  the  bodily  order  into  experiences 
of  the  soul,  making  possible  a  reversion  to  pythagoreanism  (pp. 
318-20).  Although  Zollner  essayed  to  explain  the  rise  of  industry 
and  of  science,  together  with  the  reasons  for  social  decadence,  he 
forgot  the  office  of  art,  dear  to  Nietzsche,  because  with  art  lay  the 
potency  of  the  future.  In  fine,  Nietzsche's  contact  with  physical 
science  rendered  it  necessary  for  him  to  expand  Wagnerism  ration- 
ally. Nor  was  he  to  stop  at  physics  and  chemistry. 

Darwin's  fermentum  cognitionis,  known  to  Nietzsche  through  the 
several  reactions  of  F.  A.  Lange,  Oscar  Schmidt,  and  Nageli,  involved 
other  issues.  At  this  juncture,  personal  contact  with  L.  Eiitimeyer, 
the  paleontologist,  professor  of  zoology  and  comparative  anatomy  at 
Basle,  a  "philosophical  spirit"  in  a  day  when  the  riches  of  observa- 
tion and  experiment  had  atrophied  generalization  (p.  332),  exerted 
decisive  influence,  causing  Nietzsche  to  substitute  for  the  individual- 
istic struggle  for  existence  a  genetic,  and  neo-lamarckian,  elan  vitale. 
This  "prime  vital  energy"  may  portend  much,  mayhap  even  the 
birth  of  a  supreme  race.  For,  as  Eiitimeyer  had  the  hardihood  to 
suggest,  "Notre  squelette  porte  en  lui  les  possibilites  d'une  evolution 
vlterieure,  autant  que  toute  autre  forme  du  squelette  vertebre"  (p. 
343).  Hence  Nietzsche's  preoccupation  thus  early  with  the  possi- 
bility of  an  ascent  to  a  higher  type  of  humanity.  Here,  then,  is  a 
mystic  positivism  and,  to  the  extent  of  its  mysticism,  it  demands  a 
reckoning  with  religion. 

Accordingly,  chapter  II  deals  with  the  "unseasonable"  essay  on 
D.  F.  Strauss.  The  friendship  with  that  "vieitte  fitte  fanatisee" 


BOOK  REVIEWS  249 

(p.  352),  the  pontificating  bas-Ueu,  Malwida  von  Meysenbug;  the 
marked  influence  of  the  views  of  Paul  de  Lagarde  (Gottingen)  about 
Protestantism,  Catholicism,  and  Judaism;  and  of  Franz  Overbeck's 
Vber  die  Christlichkeit  der  heutigen  Theologie  (p.  368  f.)  added  to 
the  ferment.  As  Nietzsche  saw  things  now,  Cosima  Wagner 
threatened  to  corrupt  her  husband,  Strauss  to  corrupt  the  German 
people — the  one  by  reactionary  faith,  the  other  by  equally  reac> 
tionary  science.  So  Nietzsche  agonizes.  The  tract  on  History  re- 
sults and,  with  that  on  Schopenhauer  as  Educator,  he  passes  beyond 
Wagnerism,  to  begin  the  "Renaissance  of  tragic  philosophy  in 
Germany"  (p.  416).  Wagner  must  be  constrained  to  reconstruct 
his  universe  of  values,  or  a  final  break  can  not  be  averted.  Chapter 
IV  diagnoses  the  symptoms  which  led  to  the  break,  and  brought 
Nietzsche's  "L'affranchissement"  (the  title  of  the  chapter).  Suffice 
it  to  say  that  association  with  Jacob  Burckhardt,  another  member 
of  the  stimulating  circle  at  Basle,  supplied  a  decisive  factor.  The 
volume  closes  with  a  (brief  appendix  on  Nietzsche's  philological  writ- 
ings, exploited  recently  by  Ernst  Howald  in  his  Friedrich  Nietzsche 
und  die  klassische  Philologie  (1920). 

It  were  superfluous  to  praise  Andler's  breadth  of  knowledge, 
presented  with  the  unique  talent  of  his  people  for  clear  and  crisp 
exposition.  The  'book  marks  another  step  in  an  indispensable  guide 
to  Nietzsche's  Odyssey  of  the  spirit.  Similar  review  of  Volume  III 
will  follow  soon. 

E.  M.  WENLEY. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  MICHIGAN. 

The  Psychology  of  Everyday  Life.  Pp.  ix  -f-  164.  The  Psychol- 
ogy of  Industry.  Pp.  xi  -|-  148.  JAMES  DREVER.  London : 
Methuen  &  Co.,  Ltd.  1921. 

These  two  books  are  written  for  the  general  reader  in  that 
happy  popular  style  which  is  the  peculiar  gift  of  the  British  and 
the  despair  of  Continental  writers.  Here  and  there  a  striking  ex- 
pression makes  a  scientific  fact  stand  out  with  the  vividness  of  a 
poetic  phrase,  as,  e.g.,  "Experience  is  itself  living."  "The  world 
of  make-believe  is  a  self -created  world." 

In  the  first  volume  nearly  all  the  major  points  of  modern  psy- 
chology have  been  touched  upon,  though  rather  lightly  it  must  be 
confessed.  His  treatment  of  the  emotional  life  is  rather  better  than 
that  of  some  other  subjects  and  he  seems  particularly  fortunate  in 
his  application  of  the  psychological  theories  of  Freud  to  this  phase 
of  conscious  life.  The  motive  in  writing  the  book  is  the  belief, 
"that  for  all  those  arts  and  sciences  which  are  concerned  with  the 
human  factor  in  the  world  process  in  any  of  its  phases  the  science 


250  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  psychology  is  as  fundamental  as  is  the  science  of  physics  for  all 
those  arts  and  sciences  which  are  concerned  with  physical  proc- 
esses." (P.  v.) 

The  second  volume  might  be  classed  as  applied  psychology  and 
treats  of  the  topics  pertaining  to  industry  and  commerce,  such  as 
the  intelligence  and  fitness  of  the  worker;  the  function  of  mental 
engineering;  the  problem  of  fatigue;  economy  of  learning  and 
working;  and  the  theory  and  art  of  salesmanship.  Standard  tests 
and  experiments  are  described  and  interpreted  from  the  author's 
standpoint,  which  he  tries  to  keep  strictly  psychological  in  distinc- 
tion from  that  of  the  economist  or  the  social  philosopher. 

These  books  might  well  be  read  by  every  teacher  of  psychology 
by  way  of  learning  how  the  subject  may  be  related  to  life  in  a  way 
to  attract  and  benefit  the  average  student.  Their  chief  appeal, 
however,  must  be  to  those  persons  whose  work  is  principally  that  of 
dealing  with  human  relationships  such  as  the  educator,  the  social 
worker,  the  minister,  the  lawyer,  and  the  employer  of  large  num- 
bers of  his  fellow  men. 

L.  PEAEL  BOGGS. 

URBANA,  ILL. 

JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

MIND.  October,  1921.  The  External  World  (pp.  385-409) : 
C.  D.  BROAD. -A  discussion  of  the  meaning  of  sensible  appearance 
in  the  light  of  recent  realistic  theory,  the  essence  of  which  is  "that 
whenever  I  judge  that  something  appears  to  me  to  have  the  quality 
q  there  must  be  an  object  with  which  I  am  acquainted  which  really 
does  have  the  quality  q.  This  object  is  the  sensum."  The  sensum, 
sensation,  and  the  physical  object  must  be  distinguished.  Some 
Explanations  (pp.  409-429):  S.  ALEXANDER. -A  reply  to  criti- 
cisms of  Space,  Time,  and  Deity.  Literary  Truth  and  Realism,  The 
Aesthetic  Function  of  Literature  and  its  Relation  to  Philosophy 
(II)  (pp.  429-444):  P.  LEON.  -  Criticism  of  expressionist  and 
other  views  of  art  and  a  "re-statement,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
literature,  of  the  old  formal  view  of  art.  ..."  Discussion.  The 
Meaning  of  "Meaning"  (pp.  444  417) :  F.  C.  S.  SCHILLEB.  Criti- 
cal Notices.  W.  E.  JOHNSON,  Logic,  Pt.  I:  J.  GIBSON.  D.  Faw- 
cett,  Divine  Imagining:  J.  S.  MACKENZIE.  Viscount  Haldane,  The 
Reign  of  Relativity:  H.  WILDON  CARR.  New  Books.  Eugenic  Rig- 
nano,  Psychologic  du  Raisonnement :  F.  C.  B.  Adolf o  Levi,  Scep- 
tica:  A.  E.  TAYLOR.  Graham  Wallas,  Our  Social  Heritage: 
V.  M.  BENECKE.  J.  J.  Putnam,  Addresses  on  Psycho-analysis:  E. 
PRIDEAUX.  Wm.  Brown,  Psychology  and  Psychotherapy:  W. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  251 

WHATELY  SMITH.  J.  Larguier  des  Bancels,  Introduction  a  la  Psy- 
chologic: JAMES  DBEVEB.  Robert  Briffault,  Psyche's  Lamp:  A 
Revaluation  of  Psychological  Principles  as  Foundation  of  all 
Thought:  L.  S.  S.  J.  O'Callaghan,  Dual  Evolution:  L.  J.  RUS- 
SELL. Aristide  Gabelli,  II  Metodo  di  Insegnamento  nelle  Scuole 
Elementari  d'ltalia;  Bertrando  Spaventa,  La  Liberta  d'  Insegna- 
mento; M.  Casotti,  Introduzione  alia  Pedagogia:  B.  BOSANQUET. 
L.  Cazamian,  L' Evolution  Psychologic  et  la  Litterature  en  An- 
gleterre:  I.  A.  RICHARDS.  Felix  Weltsch,  "Gnade  und  Freiheit": 
JAMES  LINDSAY.  Joseph  Jastrow,  The  Psychology  of  Conviction: 
C.  W.  V.  James  Drever,  The  Psychology  of  Industry:  B.  M. 
Drs.  Ferenczi,  K.  Abraham,  E.  Simmel,  E.  Jones,  Psycho-analysis 
and  War  Neuroses:  E.  PBIDEAUX.  Knight  Dunlap,  Mysticism, 
Freudianism,  and  Scientific  Psychology:  J.  W.  S.  The  Works  of 
Aristotle,  Vol.  X:  Politics,  by  Benjamin  Jowett;  Oeconomica,  by 
E.  S.  Forster;  Atheniensium  Respublica,  by  Sir  F.  G.  Kenyon: 
A.  E.  TAYLOR.  Antonio  Aliotta,  L'Estetica  del  Croce  e  la  Crisi 
dell'  Idealismo  Moderno:  H.  W.  C.  Giovanni  Gentile,  Giordano 
Bruno  e  il  Pensiero  del  Rinascimento :  J.  L.  M.  Pasquale  Gatti, 
L'Unita  del  Pensiero  Leopardiano:  A.  E.  TAYLOR.  E.  Cunning- 
ham, Relativity,  the  Electron  Theory,  and  Gravitation:  C.  D.  B. 
A.  A.  Robb,  The  Absolute  Relations  of  Time  and  Space:  C.  D.  B. 
W.  Tudor  Jones,  The  Training  of  Mind  and  Witt;  and  The  Mak- 
ing of  Personality:  F.  C.  S.  S.  De  Witt  H.  Parker,  The  Princi- 
ples of  Aesthetics:  I.  A.  RICHARDS.  Ch.  Lalo,  L'Art  et  la  Vie 
Sociale:  I.  A.  R.  Philosophical  Periodicals.  Notes.  <(  Common 
Sense  and  the  Rudiments  of  Philosophy":  CHARLES  E.  HOOPER. 
A  French  Historian  of  the  Philosophies  of  the  Middle  Ages:  Fran- 
gois-Joseph  Picavet  (1851-1921) :  M.  P.  RAMSAY. 

Dilthey,  Wilhelm.  "Weltanshauung  und  Analyse  des  Menschen  seit 
Renaissance  und  Reformation.  (Gesammelte  Schriften,  II 
Band.)  Leipzig:  B.  G.  Teubner.  1921.  Pp.  xi  +  528.  $7.20. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

The  third  International  Moral  Education  Congress  will  be  held 
at  Geneva  on  July  28,  29,  31  and  August  1  of  the  current  year.  The 
object  of  these  congresses,  of  which  the  first  was  held  in  1908  in  Lon- 
don and  the  second  in  1912  at  the  Hague,  is  to  serve  the  cause  of 
moral  education,  both  inside  and  outside  of  schools  and  universities, 
irrespective  of  religion  and  nationality.  The  special  theme  of  the 
forthcoming  congress  will  be  international  good  will  and  the  ways 
of  promoting  it.  The  teaching  of  history  will  receive  much  attention. 
The  official  languages  will  be  French,  English,  Italian,  German  and 


252  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Esperanto.  Papers  giving  a  general  survey  of  a  subject  may  fill 
about  30  minutes;  shorter  and  more  technical  ones  may  fill  10. 
Papers  will  be  followed  by  discussion.  There  will  be  a  reading  room, 
to  contain  as  much  as  can  be  brought  together  which  bears  upon 
the  purpose  of  the  congress.  One  exhibition  will  be  of  books  for 
young  people,  handbooks  and  newspapers  of  a  kind  to  avoid.  Only 
about  thirty  papers  can  be  printed,  owing  to  the  cost  of  publication, 
but  it  is  hoped  that  these  will  be  of  high  merit,  and  that  the  congress 
will  make  a  serious  contribution  to  a  field  in  which  knowledge  and 
cooperation  have  never  been  more  needed.  The  chairman  of  the 
executive  council  is  Sir  Frederick  Pollock. 

A  meeting  of  the  Aristotelian  Society  was  held  on  March  6,  1922, 
Professor  J.  S.  Mackenzie  in  the  chair.  Professor  S.  N.  Dasgupta 
read  a  paper  on  "The  Logic  of  the  Vedanta,"  a  synopsis  of  which 
follows :  The  earliest  Upanisads,  forming  the  concluding  part  of  the 
Vedic  literature,  were  completed  certainly  before  500  B.  C.  The 
main  doctrine  found  in  them  is  that  self  is  the  ultimate  reality. 
This  self  is  not  the  Ego  but  pure  consciousness,  which  was  regarded 
as  supremely  unchangeable.  The  early  Buddist  philosophy  sought 
to  prove  that  everything  was  changing  and  that  there  was  nothing 
which  could  be  regarded  as  permanent.  The  nihilistic  school  of 
Buddhism  as  interpreted  by  Nagarjuna  and  Aryadeya  (100  A.  D.) 
demonstrated,  by  critical  and  dialectical  reasoning  of  the  type  which 
Mr.  Bradley  has  used,  that  our  ordinary  conceptions  of  experience 
are  absolutely  relative  and  are  therefore  indefinite  and  indefinable. 
The  idealistic  Buddhists  accepted  this  position  and  held  that  all 
wordly  experience  is  due  to  mental  construction.  The  Vedanta, 
as  explained  by  Sankara,  and  as  interpreted  by  Sriharsa  and  Mad- 
Lusuilana  Sarasvati  and  others,  held  that  pure  consciousness,  as 
revealed  in  immediate  experience  and  as  distinct  from  its  particular 
form  and  content,  is  self-contained  and  absolutely  real.  Particular 
forms  are  relative  and  mutually  interdependent.  They  are  definable 
either  as  being  or  as  non-being  for  they  participate  in  the  nature  of 
both.  They  are  the  modifications  of  separate  logical  category  called 
the  indefinite  and  have  the  same  sort  of  logical  status  as  illusions. 
They  appear  as  existent  by  virtue  of  their  relation  with  pure  con- 
sciousness which  is  absolutely  unchangeable  and  self-contained  and 
immediate.  Everything  which  has  any  form  or  content  is  thus  a 
joint  manifestation  of  the  indefinite.  The  nature  of  all  that  is  rela- 
tive is  that  it  has  being  in  some  sense  and  it  has  no  being  in  another, 
and  it  can  not  therefore  be  regarded  either  as  positive  or  negative. 
This  necessitates  the  acceptance  of  the  indefinite  as  a  separate  log- 
ical category  which  explains  the  logical  status  of  all  that  is  relative. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  10  MAY  11,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  FORM  OF  PHILOSOPHICAL  INTELLIGIBILITY  1 

"TT~NDER  this  title  I  wish  to  call  attention  to  an  aspect  of  a  very 
^  old  and  familiar  problem — that  of  the  nature  of  philosophy. 
We  habitually  assign  to  philosophy  the  task  of  "explaining"  the 
world,  or  of  rendering  experience  "intelligible."  Now  is  it  pos- 
sible to  specify  more  exactly  what  is  involved  in  this  requirement? 
What  is  it  to  explain  or  to  render  intelligible  in  the  philosophical 
sense,  and  what  is  the  form  or  logic  in  which  philosophy  can  be  re- 
quired to  attain  rationality?  It  would  seem  necessary  to  under- 
stand as  clearly  and  definitely  as  possible  what  type  of  explanation 
philosophy  may  properly  be  expected  to  furnish  before  any  discus- 
sion is  in  order  regarding  its  competency  to  fulfill  its  task,  or  con- 
cerning the  relative  value  and  pertinency  of  various  systems. 

The  central  position  that  the  problem  occupies  logically  is  not, 
however,  its  only  claim  to  consideration.  The  failure  to  discrimi- 
nate between  different  forms  of  explanation  has  frequently  given 
rise  to  practical  misunderstandings  regarding  the  fruitfulness  and 
value  of  philosophical  study  itself.  It  would  be  hard  to  find  a  better 
illustration  of  the  fact  that  discontent  and  disillusionment  often 
have  their  sources  in  unreasonable  expectations  and  impossible  de- 
mands. Complaints  are  brought  against  philosophy — not  merely 
by  outsiders,  but  by  its  professed  students  as  well — for  a  strange 
variety  of  reasons:  because  it  does  not  give  us  demonstrations  like 
mathematics,  or  new  facts  like  the  natural  sciences,  or  esthetic  en- 
joyment like  poetry,  or  a  technique  for  transforming  education  and 
social  life  in  accordance  with  the  demands  of  the  age.  Or,  again, 
the  demand  is  that  philosophy  shall  furnish  a  statement  of  the  most 
general  relations  of  existence,  analogous  to  but  more  inclusive  than 
the  fundamental  principles  of  mathematics.  Now  I  do  not  say  that 
all  these  requirements  are  artificial  and  suggested  merely  by  external 
analogies — though  I  think  that  some  of  them  undoubtedly  are — nor 
is  it  necessary  to  assume  that  on  examination  they  would  appear 
mutually  inconsistent.  They  have  been  mentioned  only  to  illustrate 
the  variety  of  the  demands  that  are  made  upon  philosophy,  and  to 

1  Bead  before  the  Eastern  Branch,  of  American  Philosophical  Association 
at  Vassal-  College,  December  29,  1921. 

253 


254  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

suggest  the  corresponding  necessity  from  a  practical  point  of  view 
of  such  an  inquiry  as  is  suggested  by  the  title  of  this  paper. 

In  considering  this  question  it  is  helpful,  I  think,  to  make  an 
attempt  to  distinguish  genuine  philosophical  problems  from  those 
that  are  artificial.  Of  course  such  a  distinction  can  not  be  made 
in  any  external  fashion  by  setting  up  a  preliminary  definition.  In 
philosophy,  more  than  in  any  other  type  of  inquiry,  the  formulation 
of  the  problem  and  its  answer  can  never  be  sharply  separated.  To 
succeed  in  asking  a  reasonable  question  is  already  in  some  measure 
to  see  one's  way  to  an  answer.  One  must  begin,  then,  by  attempt- 
ing to  appreciate  rightly  the  objective  situation  and  its  demands.  A 
genuine  philosophical  problem  is  one  that  is  objectively  grounded 
and  does  not  spring  merely  from  the  associatively  directed  fancy  of 
a  subjective  interest.  There  must  underlie  it  an  order  of  experience 
that  is  already  fundamentally  organized  in  accordance  with  rational 
principles,  and  it  is  from  the  demands  of  this  experience  that  philos- 
ophy as  a  consciously  directed  activity  must  proceed.  It  will  of 
course  be  necessary  to  bring  up  for  further  examination  and  criticism 
principles  previously  received;  but  in  doing  this  philosophy  must 
rest  its  case  upon  an  order  of  experience  that  is  taken,  at  least 
provisionally,  as  reasonable  and  secure.  Thus,  while  one  may 
reasonably  question  the  validity  of  any  particular  fact  or  phase  of 
experience,  one  can  not  intelligibly  question  the  validity  of  experi- 
ence as  a  whole.  The  beginning  of  all  philosophy  consists  in  an 
acceptance  of  the  world-order  of  our  own  time  and  civilization,  and 
from  these  roets  all  its  genuine  problems  spring. 

These  considerations  when  applied  help  to  protect  us  against  a 
good  many  pseudo-problems  that  are  popularly  supposed  to  be  the 
special  interest  of  philosophy.  It  is  not  the  business  of  philosophy, 
as  Lotze  was  fond  of  remarking,  to  prove  that  the  world  exists  or 
to  demonstrate  how  it  is  made.  Philosophy  has  not  to  show  us  how 
to  make  a  world,  but  to  help  us  in  understanding  the  actual  world 
in  which  we  find  ourselves.  The  genuine  problems  of  philosophy 
are  natural  problems,  not  reached  by  any  artificial  straining,  but 
generated  by  the  demands  of  a  human  life  to  know  itself  and  to 
become  at  home  in  its  world. 

There  is  always  a  special  danger  that  when  philosophy  is  carried 
on  largely  by  schools  and  schoolmen  it  may  become  artificial  through 
too  great  an  emphasis  upon  formal  completeness  and  the  require- 
ments of  technical  demonstration.  It  would  be  quite  in  order  to 
raise  the  question,  "Are  we  Scholastics?  "  Scholasticism  has  of 
course  its  merits,  and  I  am  not  arguing  in  favor  of  dilettantism,  or 
lack  of  earnestness  and  seriousness  in  carrying  on  philosophical  in- 
quiries, but  against  making  what  is  merely  technical  and  abstract 


PHILOSOPHICAL  INTELLIGIBILITY  255 

the  end  and  goal.  It  is  of  course  to  .be  admitted  that  for  certain 
preliminary  inquiries  in  philosophy  technical  methods  and  a  rigor- 
ously defined  terminology  are  necessary.  But  two  things  should  be 
borne  in  mind:  first,  that  such  technical  inquiries  are  a  part  of 
philosophy  only  in  so  far  as  they  directly  or  indirectly  throw  light 
upon  some  genuine  problem,  and,  secondly,  that  the  philosopher 
by  profession  is  not  thereby  set  apart  from  his  fellows  and  dedicated 
to  some  precious  but  obscure  inquiry  in  which  they  have  neither 
part  nor  lot.  The  important  matter  is  to  rid  thought  of  abstractions 
that  are  not  instrumental  to  concrete  knowledge,  and  as  little  to 
accept  our  problems  ready-made  from  the  schoolmen  of  the  present 
day  as  from  those  of  the  past.  Philosophy,  as  criticism  that  is  based 
upon  life,  has  first  of  all  the  function  of  showing  the  irrationality 
and  illegitimacy  of  many  questions,  both  contemporary  and  tradi- 
tional. 

But  the  mere  resolve  to  occupy  one's  thought  with  the  concrete 
is  not  enough :  it  is  also  necessary  to  proceed  to  it  through  criticism, 
i.e.,  though  a  natural  dialectic  of  thought.  That  way  is  long  and 
difficult,  and  is  in  general  the  path  which  the  classical  systems  of 
philosophy  have  tried  to  follow. 

On  the  other  hand,  I  can  not  help  thinking  that  in  some  of  the 
present-day  movements  that  advertise  themselves  as  "new"  and 
"scientific"  there  is  plainly  marked  a  tendency  to  turn  away  from 
one  form  of  abstraction  in  order  to  take  refuge  in  another.  The 
desire  to  direct  philosophy  into  more  fruitful  channels  doubtless 
underlies  the  effort  to  assimilate  its  procedure  to  that  of  the  special 
sciences.  The  traditional  form  of  philosophical  inquiry,  it  is  said, 
is  neither  logically  convincing  nor  practically  fruitful,  while  con- 
temporary science  offers  an  example  of  an  increase  and  systematiza- 
tion  of  positive  facts  that  represent  a  solid  achievement  both  on 
account  of  its  certainty  and  of  its  service  to  society.  Hence  arises 
the  demand  that  philosophy  shall  be  reformed  by  the  adoption  of 
the  scientific  method,  and  made  to  yield  conclusions  that  are  rigidly 
demonstrable  and  capable  of  fruitful  application. 

Now  one  may  sympathize  in  large  measure  with  the  motives  of 
these  reformers  without  being  ready  to  accept  their  somewhat 
pessimistic  diagnosis  of  the  condition  of  philosophy  or  approving 
the  remedies  they  propose  to  employ.  That  philosophical  inquiry 
should  be  carried  on  with  systematic  thoroughness  and  with  the 
utmost  attention  to  real  facts  and  willingness  to  follow  where  the 
argument  leads,  no  one  would  wish  to  deny.  Indeed,  only  on  these 
terms  is  philosophy  true  to  its  name.  But  this  is  not  to  assert  that 
it  must  abandon  its  own  problems  and  procedure  and  seek  for  a 
place  among  the  sciences.  Here  again  I  would  suggest  the  possi- 


256  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

bility  that  dissatisfaction  with  historical  philosophy  has  its  source 
in  a  misunderstand'!  11  LT  in  regard  to  the  form  of  intelligibility  at 
which  its  representatives  have  aimed.  May  it  not  be  true  that  the 
historical  systems  seem  to  certain  persons  to  have  little  value  just  be- 
cause they  themselves  are  interested  only  in  a  different  type  of  prob- 
lem, and  that  this  fact  explains  why  they  seem  to  themselves  to  have 
received  a  stone  when  they  asked  for  bread  T 

Apart  from  religion,  there  are  three  consciously  directed  ap- 
proaches through  which  the  mind  may  be  said  to  attempt  to  render 
the  world  familiar  to  itself — those  of  science,  of  philosophy,  and  of 
art.  In  ordinary  life  these  interests  are  not  clearly  defined  and 
differentiated,  and  in  every  normal  individual  they  are  all  present 
and  influence  each  other  in  some  degree.  But  however  intimate 
their  relation  in  the  life  of  any  individual,  it  is  essential  that  one 
form  of  problem  should  not  be  confused  with  another.  The  form  of 
intelligibility  that  philosophy  seeks,  and  in  some  measure  attains,  is 
not  that  of  science  and  not  that  of  art,  nor  is  it  any  admixture  of 
the  two,  though  it  has  relations  with  both.  Leaving  for  the  present 
the  nature  of  art  out  of  account,  we  may  consider  some  of  the  funda- 
mental distinctions  between  scientific  and  philosophical  explanation. 

One  or  two  preliminary  remarks  are,  however,  necessary  to  avoid 
misunderstanding.  In  the  first  place,  the  distinction  between  these 
two  modes  of  inquiry  does  not  exclude,  but  rather  provides  for, 
mutual  aid  and  supplementation  in  practise.  The  effort  to  explain 
the  world  is  a  human  undertaking  and  is  carried  on  by  human  beings, 
not  by  the  abstractions  we  sometimes  name  "the  philosopher"  and 
' '  the  scientist. ' '  To  ensure  genuine  progress  in  any  field  it  is  neces- 
sary that  the  two  forms  of  inquiry  should  take  note  of  each  other, 
even  that  they  should  interpenetrate  each  other  within  the  same  mind. 
I  have  tried  at  various  times  to  state  and  illustrate  my  understanding 
of  necessary  connection  between  them,  and  of  the  nature  of  the  dialec- 
tic by  means  of  which  they  are  connected.  At  present  I  wish  to 
insist  that  it  is  only  by  keeping  clear  the  essential  differences  that 
the  true  relation  between  them  can  be  understood. 

The  general  question  regarding  the  relations  of  philosophy  and 
the  sciences  has,  then,  many  aspects  which  must  at  present  be  left 
out  of  account.  What  I  wish  to  emphasize  is  that  the  demands 
of  explanation  in  the  two  fields  are  not  identical,  and  that  a  com- 
plete explanation  in  one  set  of  terms  has  no  immediate  relevancy 
as  an  answer  to  a  question  raised  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  other 
inquiry.  The  scientific  explanation  of  why  Socrates  is  sitting  in 
prison  awaiting  the  execution  of  his  sentence,  stated  in  terms  of  the 
contraction  of  the  muscles  of  his  legs  and  the  revolutions  of  his 
bones  in  the  socket  joints  does  not  furnish  the  kind  of  explanation 


PHILOSOPHICAL  INTELLIGIBILITY  257 

that  is  demanded.  What  is  required  is  to  supply  the  context  in 
terms  of  the  personality  and  moral  character  of  Socrates.  It  is  not 
a  mere  difference  of  substituting  a  teleological  for  a  mechanical 
explanation,  as  might  appear  from  the  illustration.  That  the  form 
of  philosophical  intelligibility  always  does  involve  teleology,  is,  I 
think,  true.  Nevertheless  it  is  necessary  to  carry  the  matter  further 
since  there  is  a  superficial  type  of  teleological  explanation  that  has  no 
claim  to  the  title  of  philosophy,  just  as  there  are  causal  explanations 
that  can  not  properly  be  regarded  as  scientific. 

It  may  throw  additional  light  upon  the  question  before  us  to 
ask  what  legitimate  demand  of  our  intelligence  remains  unsatisfied 
after  the  scientific  account  is  complete.  What  is  still  lacking  to 
comprehension  ?  It  may  be  said  that  the  sciences  make  us  familiar 
with  the  general  framework  of  reality  and  furnish  a  kind  of  inven- 
tory of  the  different  types  of  things  contained  therein  by  exhibiting 
how  they  may  be  thought  of  as  compounded  in  certain  uniform 
ways  of  simpler  events  or  elements.  The  laws  expressing  the  rela- 
tionships of  these  elements  are  at  the  same  time,  as  Bacon  points  out, 
rules  by  means  of  which  they  may  be  constructed.  Now  although 
this  type  of  explanation  is  indispensable,  and  may  even  seem  to 
satisfy  all  justifiable  demands  in  regard  to  certain  fields  of  reality,  it 
does  not  give  us  any  insight  regarding  the  nature  of  the  significant 
individual  things  by  which  we  are  surrounded  and  in  relation  to 
which  we  live.  On  the  contrary,  it  obliterates  all  real  individuality 
and  reduces  everything  to  identical  elements  or  events.  It  yields 
knowledge  in  the  form  of  general  concepts  that  do  not  directly  apply 
to  concrete  individual  wholes,  but  to  the  abstractly  simplified  rela- 
tions of  ideally  defined  units. 

Now  conceivably  in  the  realm  of  what  we  call  nature  it  might  be 
possible  by  substituting  poetry  and  other  forms  of  art  to  dispense 
entirely  with  the  philosophical  mode  of  inquiry.  I  have  a  friend 
who  sometimes  remarks,  "I  never  feel  any  need  of  philosophy. 
When  I  turn  from  mathematics  I  fall  back  on  poetry."  That  atti- 
tude seems  comprehensible,  as  I  have  said,  so  far  as  the  realm  of 
outer  nature  is  concerned,  though  even  there  I  believe  it  would  not 
be  difficult  to  show  that  experience  involves  a  relation  to  actual  indi- 
vidual wholes  whose  nature  demands  comprehension  in  intellectual 
and  not  merely  in  imaginative  terms.  However  that  may  be,  it  is 
certainly  true  that  human  nature  and  the  world  of  social  and  histor- 
ical life  have  always  formed  the  central  interest  of  philosophy,  and  of 
these  the  attitude  in  question  simply  renounces  all  critical  and  co- 
herent knowledge.  For  the  sciences  based  on  the  logic  of  mathemat- 
ical calculation  recognize  no  individuals  and  can  furnish  no  insight 


258  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

into  the  reciprocal  human  relations  that  constitute  the  social  and 
historical  life  of  man. 

What  we  seek  under  the  name  of  philosophy  is  an  understanding 
based  on  reflective  criticism  and  observation,  of  the  individuals  and 
types  of  individuals  that  make  up  the  world  we  live  in.  This 
process  of  reflection,  it  is  evident,  must  both  presuppose  and  issue 
in  a  knowledge  of  the  self.  I  know  of  no  better  description  of 
philosophy  than  as  the  most  fully  integrated  effort  of  man  to  estab- 
lish relations  with  his  world  and  thus  to  attain  to  the  familiarity 
and  confidence  that  come  from  understanding. 

Where  shall  we  look  for  a  realized  exemplar  of  that  kind  of 
intelligibility!  Philosophy,  as  Hegel  loved  to  say,  can  not  be  real 
as  mere  desire  for  knowledge,  but  only  through  recognizing  itself 
as  knowledge  already  implicitly  realized.  If  science  does  not  give 
us  the  form  of  knowledge  we  seek,  where  is  it  actually  to  be  found  t 
In  the  classical  systems  of  philosophy,  doubtless.  But  it  seems  to  me 
that  a  familiar  illustration  of  the  kind  of  insight  that  constitutes 
philosophy  may  be  drawn  from  the  understanding  that  we  have  of 
that  part  of  the  world  with  which  we  are  most  familiar,  such  as  the 
circle  of  the  home,  or  the  life  of  a  small  community  whose  members 
have  known  each  other  long  and  intimately.  In  such  situations  the 
spirit  of  the  whole  is  comprehended  as  the  common  life  of  which  all 
the  individuals  partake,  and  in  terms  of  which  their  relations  to 
each  other  seem  natural  and  reasonable.  This  kind  of  understanding 
is  of  the  essence  of  logic,  though  it  is  rarely  drawn  out  into  a  system 
of  abstract  propositions.  But  at  its  best  it  holds  within  it,  as  it  were 
in  solution,  the  result  of  countless  observations  and  analyses,  and  is 
thus  supported  by  all  kinds  of  lore — historical,  scientific,  psycho- 
logical— constituting  a  richness  of  concrete  detail  that  has  been 
harmonized  and  blended  into  the  form  of  immediate  familiarity. 
The  depth  and  significance  of  the  immediacy  are  proportional  to 
the  attention  and  insight  that  have  gone  into  processes  that  have 
led  up  to  it.  Such  understanding  does  not  come  by  nature,  or 
through  mere  unreflective  contact,  but  is  the  product  of  accurate 
observations  and  of  well-disciplined  and  sympathetic  imagination. 
It  is  no  blind  oracle  pronouncing  ambiguous  conclusions,  but  has  its 
witness  within  it  and  is  able  to  supply  the  context  that  renders  its 
judgments  intelligible.  It  may  accordingly  be  said  that  this  type 
of  knowledge  is  philosophical  in  the  degree  in  which  it  attains 
systematic  completeness  of  view  in  concrete  form.  It  comprehends 
individuals  of  different  orders  in  the  form  of  a  significant  and  con- 
crete unity  by  supplying  the  context  that  gives  to  them  the  form  of 
a  self-subsisting  whole. 

Objection  may,  however,  be  raised  against  accepting  this  familiar 


PHILOSOPHICAL  INTELLIGIBILITY  259 

type  of  knowledge  as  an  illustration  of  the  true  form  of  philosophical 
intelligibility  on  the  ground  that  the  latter  must  rest  upon  rigorously 
demonstrated  propositions  that  command  universal  consent.  Uni- 
versality and  necessity,  we  have  been  often  told,  is  the  true  form  of 
philosophy.  There  is  a  truth  in  that  statement,  but  the  philosophi- 
cal form  of  universality  and  necessity  is  not  that  which  belongs  to 
abstract  propositions.  Science  is  a  system  of  abstract  propositions, 
but  the  demand  for  this  type  of  demonstration  in  philosophy  rests 
upon  a  confusion  of  ideas.  Eigorous  logical  proof  of  the  type 
demanded  by  science  is  always  purchased  at  the  cost  of  abstraction, 
as  is  most  clearly  illustrated  in  the  case  of  mathematics;  the  more 
complete  the  abstraction  from  reality  the  more  compelling  is  the 
nature  of  the  formal  demonstration.  Just  because  philosophy  is  oc- 
cupied with  the  relations  of  concrete  individuals  and  systems  of 
individuals,  the  logic  of  general  propositions  can  not  be  its  final  test 
or  form  of  truth. 

The  difficulty  is  still  likely  to  be  urged,  however,  that  what  is 
not  expressible  in  propositions  that  can  be  formally  demonstrated  is 
but  subjective  opinion,  and  can  never  furnish  a  common  basis  for 
life  or  society.  This  would  be  a  serious  objection  if  it  were  true. 
But  it  rests,  I  think,  upon  a  misunderstanding  of  the  nature  pf 
knowledge  as  a  process  of  systematic  concretion,  a  movement  from 
the  abstract  to  the  concrete.  In  the  first  place,  demonstration  of 
the  type  described  by  formal  logic  has  its  place  and  function  only 
within  this  total  process.  It  always  presupposes  an  objective  world 
of  fact  upon  which  the  common  intelligence  of  individuals  rests. 
The  abstract  method  can  operate  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  supported  by 
a  concrete  basis  of  organized  fact.  One  could  infer  nothing  in  a  world 
of  mere  assumptions.  And  secondly,  in  actual  reasoning  there  is  al- 
ways the  further  question  after  the  formal  correctness  of  a  conclusion 
has  been  accepted — the  question,  namely,  as  to  what  application  it  has, 
i.e.,  how  it  enters  concretely  into  the  world  of  reality  and  modifies 
or  further  defines  our  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  the  individual 
systems  that  compose  it. 

The  common  experience  which  forms  the  basis  of  a  common 
social  life  is,  even  on  its  intellectual  side,  wrongly  conceived  as  of  the 
inflexible  type  suggested  by  the  literal  identity  of  identically  formu- 
lated propositions.  It  is  comparatively  easy  to  agree  upon  a  com- 
mon formula;  but  no  matter  how  carefully  the  words  have  been 
defined  in  the  abstract,  the  attempt  to  apply  the  formula  is  sure  to 
reveal  differences  of  personal  opinion.  Such  formulas  have  an 
important  function  as  instruments  in  attaining  a  common  under- 
standing, and  they  serve  too  as  a  nucleus  about  which  common  feel- 
ings grow  up.  But  neither  practical  life  nor  philosophy  can  rest 


260  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

in  such  abstract  forms  of  agreement.  The  conditions  of  a  common 
life  demand  differences  no  less  than  identity.  Without  such  dif- 
ferences there  would  be  no  knowledge,  nothing  but  the  dead  level 
of  opinion  that  is  without  life  or  movement.  If  this  is  true,  the  ob- 
jectivity of  philosophy  is  not  something  guaranteeing  a  common 
platform  of  truth  that  is  once  for  all  defined  and  demonstrated.  It 
is  rather  the  concrete  basis  of  an  understanding  developed  through 
the  give  and  take  of  a  common  life. 

If  the  logic  of  philosophy  is  of  the  character  that  I  have  en- 
deavored to  sketch,  it  is  evident  that  the  oft-repeated  criticism  that 
it  obscures  differences  and  issues  in  a  block  universe  is  based  upon 
a  failure  to  distinguish  clearly  between  its  goal  and  that  of  the 
sciences.  It  is  the  logic  of  science  that  has  an  eye  only  for  uni- 
formities, while  that  of  philosophy  seeks  out  and  maintains  differ- 
ences. The  latter,  however,  does  not  rest  in  discrete  or  isolated  points 
of  view ;  for  the  principle  of  individuality  when  rightly  understood 
leads  on  to  a  system  of  individualities.  The  individual,  that  is,  just 
because  it  is  not  a  mere  particular  but  possesses  character  or  sig- 
nificance, is  a  member  of  a  world  or  system  of  individuals.  Every- 
thing however  depends  upon  rightly  apprehending  the  nature  of  the 
universal  that  at  onces  unifies  and  individualizes  its  members.  That 
is,  neither  aspect  of  the  individual  reality  must  be  taken  apart  from 
the  other.  If  we  say  that  the  individual  is  the  synthesis  of  the 
particular  and  the  universal,  we  must  remember  that  these  aspects 
have  no  meaning  apart  from  each  other,  they  are  not  elements  exist- 
ing separately  out  of  which  we  have  to  compound  the  individual 
whole.  The  universal  is  not  something  to  be  pictured  existentially, 
either  as  a  connecting  link,  or  a  common  element  in  different  individ- 
uals. Philosophy  is  indeed  speculation  or  seeing,  'but  its  light  must 
not  be  confused  with  representation  in  the  form  of  imagery.  As 
reason,  i.e.,  the  integral  mind  in  its  totality  and  completest  effort 
after  the  real  thing,  it  has  the  form  of  universality  and  freedom. 
That  is,  it  is  not  bound  down  and  controlled,  as  in  the  ordinary 
routine  of  practical  life,  by  the  first  form  of  particularity  and  hard 
isolation,  but  sees  beyond  these  and  comprehends  their  true  reality 
and  significance  in  terms  of  its  own  system  of  concrete  truth. 

The  conclusion  we  have  reached,  then,  is  that  the  philosophical 
form  of  intelligibility  is  that  of  a  concrete  universal  which  expresses 
the  inwardness  and  essence  of  individuals  through  the  grasp  of  their 
constitutive  relations.  Just  because  modern  science  is  not  concerned 
with  significant  individuals,  but  with  abstract  aspects  taken  as  bare 
"existences,"  its  universal  is  barely  conceptual  or  nominal.  A 
scientific  law  is  regarded  as  simply  a  generalized  formula  or  abbre- 
viated record  of  correlations  between  certain  abstract  aspects  of  real 


PHILOSOPHICAL  INTELLIGIBILITY  261 

things.  The  whole  purpose  of  the  inquiry  is  to  obtain  a  summary  form 
of  representing  facts  so  as  to  afford  a  convenient  and  economic  means 
of  dealing  with  them  practically.  "The  existential  point  of  view" 
is  neither  that  of  common-sense  nor  that  of  philosophy:  it  is  an 
artificial  simplification  which  has  its  own  logic  and  its  own  justifica- 
tion, adopted  and  maintained  by  scientific  procedure  in  accordance 
with  carefully  defined  assumptions.  It  may  fairly  be  characterized 
as  an  external  form  of  representation,  indispensable  for  its  own  pur- 
poses but  as  contributing  nothing  directly  to  philosophical  under- 
standing. Like  Descartes 's  material  bodies,  scientific  phenom- 
ena may  be  said  to  have  no  insides.  In  dealing  with  them  the  mind 
moves,  that  is,  on  the  plane  of  external  existence  and  represents 
or  pictures  the  relations  between  them  in  terms  of  a  logic  derived 
from  space.  The  statement  said  to  have  been  made  by  the  late 
Lord  Kelvin  that  he  could  understand  a  theory  only  when  he  was 
able  to  represent  it  in  a  drawing,  illustrates  well  the  point  I  have 
in  mind.  This  seems  to  be  the  form  of  intelligibility  toward  which 
all  the  sciences  look  as  their  ideal. 

But  philosophy  in  its  own  domain  has  no  concern  with  the  bare 
form  of  existence.  To  achieve  the  form  of  intelligibility  at  which 
it  aims  it  is  indeed  necessary  that  the  mind  shall  understand  the 
truth  that  is  contained  in  this  abstract  standpoint,  but  it  has  also  to 
free  itself  from  the  domination  of  existential  imagery  in  order  to 
rise  to  freedom  and  universality.  It  is,  however,  important  to  note 
that  freedom  from  imagery  is  not  identical  with  withdrawal  from 
what  is  actual  and  concrete.  The  real  world  is  the  world  of 
significant  individual  wholes  constituted  by  reflective  experience; 
not  that  of  the  superficial  and  conflicting  impressions  of  practical 
life. 

J.  E.  CREIGHTON. 
COENELL  UNIVERSITY. 


MEASURES  OF  INTELLIGENCE  AND  CHARACTER 


of  the  most  important  questions  that  arise  in  connection 
with  the  widespread  use  of  the  intelligence  examination  is: 
What  part  does  intelligence,  as  measured  by  such  a  test  as  the  Army 
Alpha,  play  in  success  in  an  occupation?  The  report  of  the  psy- 
chological examining  in  the  U.  S.  Army  provides  valuable  material 
pertaining  to  this  question.  The  median  intelligence  for  various 
occupations  is  given,  together  with  the  range  of  the  middle  fifty 
per  cent.  (Mem.  Nat.  Acad.  of  Sci.,  1921,  XV,  pp.  819  flf.).  The 
range  of  intelligence  within  a  given  occupation  is  great  and  the 
overlapping  among  the  occupations  is  also  great,  so  that  for  pur- 


262  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

poses  of  vocational  guidance  the  occupations  included  in  the  study 
would  have  to  be  classed  into  about  three  groups,  such  as  the  pro- 
ft-Nsional,  the  clerical  and  skilled  labor,  and  the  labor  class.  For  a 
finer  classification  other  criteria  must  be  adopted. 

Two  important  indicators  might  be  obtained  from  such  data, 
namely,  the  minimum  intelligence  needed  for  a  given  occupation; 
and  that  degree  of  intelligence  that  one  needs  in  order  to  be  better 
than  the  average  person  engaged  in  the  occupation.  The  value  of 
this  second  indicator  rests  upon  the  assumption  that  the  greater  the 
intelligence  of  the  individual  the  greater  his  success  in  any  occupa- 
tion. The  data  do  not  show  whether  or  not  this  is  the  case.  If  in- 
telligence were  the  only  condition  of  success,  then  degree  of  success 
might  be  prophesied  from  degree  of  intelligence.  But  other  de- 
termining factors  must  at  least  be  sought. 

The  views  expressed  by  the  fourteen  psychologists  who  recently 
contributed  to  a  "Symposium  on  Intelligence"  conducted  by  the 
Journal  of  Educational  Psychology  (1921,  Vol.  12,  Nos.  3,  4,  and 
5)  show  the  increasing  importance  which  is  being  attached  to  the 
so-called  character  traits.  Although,  in  every  case  but  one,  defin- 
ing intelligence  so  as  to  exclude  the  character  traits,  a  plea  was 
made  for  recognition  of  their  significance  in  determining  success. 
Even  in  college  work  where  intelligence  is  considered  a  prime  re- 
quisite, an  important  place  is  being  assigned  to  these  traits.  The 
limit  of  correlation  to  be  expected  between  an  intelligence  test  and 
performance  in  college  is  probably  between  -|-  .60  and  -f-  .65. 
Other  conditions  of  success  are  physical  health,  interest,  aggressive- 
ness, social  qualities,  etc.,  in  short  what  are  usually  comprised  in 
the  term  "character  traits"  (with  the  possible  exception  of  physi- 
cal health). 

The  statement  has  been  made  recently  that  there  are  certain 
kinds  of  work  for  which  the  optimum  degree  of  intelligence  is  not 
the  maximum  degree,  for  example,  in  the  case  of  messenger  boys, 
sales-clerks  and  even  elementary  school  teachers;  and  that  to  seek 
for  the  highest  intelligence  available  may  represent  misguided  ef- 
fort. Such  a  view  need  not  imply,  I  believe,  that  a  low  degree  of 
intelligence  is  in  itself  really  better  for  a  given  job  than  a  higher 
degree  of  intelligence  would  be,  but  rather  that  one  is  more  likely 
to  find  along  with  a  low  degree  of  intelligence  those  character  traits 
that  make  for  success  and  satisfaction  in  certain  kinds  of  work. 
One  might,  for  example,  expect  to  find  the  traits  that  bring  success 
as  a  scrub-woman  or  automatic  machine  tender  and  leading  to 
satisfaction  in  these  simple  forms  of  manual  labor  accompanying  a 
low  rather  than  a  high  intelligence. 

The  study  by  Bregman  (Journal  of  Applied  Psychology,  1921, 


MEASURES  OF  INTELLIGENCE  AND  CHARACTER  263 

V,  127-151)  of  sales-clerks  and  clerical  workers  shows  that  with  a 
given  group  of  applicants  the  more  successful  sales-clerks  come 
from  those  that  get  a  relatively  low  score  in  her  series  of  tests; 
while  the  more  successful  clerical  workers  come  from  the  group 
that  gets  the  relatively  high  score.  That  is,  these  tests  show  a  nega- 
tive correlation  with  sales  ability  and  a  positive  correlation  with 
clerical  ability.  The  tests  used  to  make  this  distinction  between 
sales-clerks  and  clerical  workers  are  those  commonly  used  as  parts 
of  intelligence  tests,  such  as  completion  of  sentences,  tests  of  in- 
formation and  the  various  kinds  of  association  tests.  When  their 
scores  are  combined  they  give  somewhat  of  an  intelligence  rating. 
Now,  is  a  relatively  low  intelligence  required  for  success  as  a 
sales-clerk,  or  does  one  succeed  in  spite  of  low  intelligence,  because 
of  the  presence  of  other  than  intelligence  traits, — the  character 
traits? 

Otis  (Journal  of  Applied  Psychology,  1920,  IV,  339-341)  found 
a  zero  correlation  between  success  as  a  mill  worker  and  perform- 
ance in  his  intelligence  test.  He  concludes  his  report  thus:  "In- 
telligence is  not  only  not  required  in  a  modern  silk  mill  for  most 
operations  but  may  even  be  a  detriment  to  steady  efficient  routine 
work.  What  qualities  are  required  remains  to  be  sought.  Whether 
they  are  measurable  is  doubtful.  They  may  be  stolidity,  patience, 
inertia  of  attention,  regularity  of  habits,  etc."  The  question  may 
be  asked:  Is  intelligence  really  a  detriment  in  such  occupations, 
or  is  it  merely  likely  to  have  accompanying  it  certain  character 
traits  not  suited  to  the  task? 

If  the  degree  of  intelligence  possessed  by  an  individual  is  to  be 
taken  as  the  indicator  of  the  presence  of  certain  desirable  or  unde- 
sirable character  traits  the  correlation  between  the  two  must  be 
high.  A  survey  of  the  available  material  on  the  relation  between 
intelligence  and  character  traits  shows  that  the  correlation  is  posi- 
tive but  that  it  will  probably  not  go  higher  than  -j-  .50.  This  cor- 
relation of  -f-  .50  accounts  for  the  fact  that  one  can  find  desirable 
character  traits  in  persons  of  very  low  intelligence.  If  the  presence 
of  one  can  not  be  taken  as  the  sign  of  the  presence  of  the  other, 
then  both  must  be  measured.  It  is  quite  important  to  find  out  the 
upper  limit  as  well  as  the  lower  limit  of  intelligence  for  a  given 
kind  of  work  merely  as  a  matter  of  economy  of  intelligence.  But 
the  need  for  simple  character  tests  is  just  as  great  or  even  greater. 
The  rate  of  labor  turnover  in  certain  types  of  work  may  well  be 
expected  to  be  greatest  among  the  workers  of  high  intelligence, 
until  a  measure  of  the  other  necessary  traits  is  used  along  with  the 
intelligence  measure  in  selecting  them.  The  following  quotation 
from  Fernald  (J.  of  Abnormal  Psychology,  1920,  XV,  4  ff.)  illus- 


264  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

trates  well  the  importance  of  measuring  both  intelligence  and 
character  in  vocational  work: 

"Two  adults,  sane  personalities,  may  be  contrasted.  The  one, 
A,  is  a  confidential  clerk  who  has  forged  his  employer's  signature 
at  least  three  times.  He  passes  'adult'  intelligence  tests  with  credit. 
His  literary  and  aesthetic  tastes  are  commendable  and  his  thought 
mechanisms  as  discovered  by  tests  and  also  as  discerned  in  ordi- 
nary social  and  business  intercourse  are  efficient  and  trustworthy. 
In  conversation  he  does  not  justify  forgery ;  but  admits  it  is  never 
justifiable.  Yet  his  love  for  fast  living,  fine  clothes,  automobiles, 
costly  companionship,  etc.,  have  occasioned  his  failure  by  forgeries 
executed  most  skillfully.  His  knowing,  inventing,  associative  and 
reasoning  capacity  is  not  at  fault;  but  his  capacity  for  resisting, 
for  denying  himself  gratification  and  for  acting  on  the  promptings 
of  his  own  good  foresight  are  at  fault.  His  weakness  is  one  of  be- 
havior and  in  the  field  of  character,  and  is  not  one  of  thinking,  and 
so  in  the  field  of  intelligence. 

"The  other  personality,  B,  is  a  farm  'chore  boy,'  an  imbecile 
as  determined  by  intelligence  tests  (I.  Q.  39),  whose  conduct  record 
is  good.  He  milks  cows,  carries  wood  and  water,  etc.,  under  direc- 
tion and  is  in  his  contracted  sphere  of  activity  an  economic  success. 
He  is  well  disposed  toward  his  environment  and  habitually  reacts 
acceptably  to  stimuli  within  his  comprehension  capacity.  His 
weakness  is  a  paucity  of  knowing,  inventing,  association,  thinking, 
etc.,  a  failure  in  the  field  of  intelligence  and  not  in  character.  The 
findings  of  intelligence  tests  only  in  these  two  cases  are  that  A  is 
of  at  least  ordinary  intelligence  while  B  is  an  imbecile.  The  find- 
ings of  character  study  only  are  that  A  is  legally  an  offender,  an 
economic  parasite  and  a  social  menace,  while  B  is  law  abiding,  a 
producer  and  no  menace.  Consideration  of  both  fields  of  inquiry 
affords  a  far  broader  and  more  illuminating  and  therefore  true 
basis  of  comparison  than  is  available  from  the  consideration  of 
either  field  alone.  In  fact,  conclusions  drawn  from  investigations 
in  either  field  to  the  exclusion  of  the  other  are  misleading." 

If  measures  of  both  these  qualities  are  necessary  for  practical 
purposes,  there  would  be  an  advantage  in  having  a  test  that  would 
measure  both  together — a  measure  of  efficiency  or  adequacy  or  com- 
petence. Such  a  test  would  make  unnecessary  any  sharp  distinc- 
tion between  what  is  intelligence  and  what  is  not,  and  would  arouse 
less  criticism  when  applied  in  business  and  industry.  The  layman 
can  not  readily  make  such  a  distinction,  while  his  crude  inference 
that  the  more  stupid  one  is  the  better  he  can  do  a  certain  job  is 
likely  both  to  arouse  opposition  and  to  introduce  certain  complica- 
tions into  the  work  of  testing.  The  distinction  is  probably  an  arti- 


MEASURES  OF  INTELLIGENCE  AND  CHARACTER  265 

ficial  one,  anyway,  depending  upon  which  of  the  many  definitions  of 
intelligence  shall  be  accepted.  In  the  "Symposium  on  Intelli- 
gence" mentioned  above  there  was  at  least  one  psychologist  who 
defined  intelligence  broadly  enough  to  include  what  are  ordinarily 
called  character  traits.  Thus  Freeman  says,  "I  conceive  intelli- 
gence to  be  a  somewhat  more  inclusive  capacity  than  is  implied 
when  it  is  used  for  a  name  for  our  present  tests.  .  .  .  The  mental 
capacity  designated  by  the  term  intelligence  seems  to  me  to  in- 
clude besides  the  elements  which  are  usually  measured  by  our 
tests,  certain  other  types  of  capacity  which  they  measure  not  at  all. 
.  .  .  The  characteristic  which  I  am  referring  to  is  sometimes  called 
temperament  or  moral  character." 

Thorndike,  in  an  article  on  "Intelligence  and  its  Uses"  (Harp- 
er's Magazine,  1920,  CXL,  227-235),  keeps  the  layman  out  of  dif- 
ficulty by  speaking  of  three  intelligences  that  every  one  possesses, 
the  abstract  intelligence,  the  mechanical  intelligence  and  the  social 
intelligence.  This  last  includes  many,  if  not  all,  of  the  so-called 
character  traits.  The  definition  of  intelligence  as  the  "capacity 
for  adaptation  or  adjustment  to  environment"  would  seem  broad 
enough  also  to  include  the  character  traits.  Fernald,  in  the  article 
quoted  above,  suggests  that  intelligence  may  vary  in  degree,  giving 
what  are  called  grades  of  intelligence,  and  in  quality,  giving  what 
are  called  character  traits. 

With  some  modification  of  content,  method  of  administration, 
and  with  supplementary  scoring  such  a  test  as  the  Army  Alpha 
might  be  made  to  yield  measures  of  neatness,  accuracy,  speed  of 
decision,  freedom  from  inertia,  assurance,  willingness  to  take  a 
chance,  tenacity  or  perseverance,  honesty,  etc.  The  total  score 
from  such  a  test  would  give  a  measure  of  efficiency  or  competence. 
By  proper  weighting  of  the  different  ingredients  of  the  total  score, 
measures  could  be  provided  for  different  occupations.  Thus,  an 
occupation  for  which  a  low  degree  of  intelligence  is  adequate,  but 
which  requires  honesty  and  steadiness  could  be  measured  by  the 
efficiency  test  with  the  intelligence  components  and  the  character 
components  given  suitable  weights.  The  result  could  be  expressed 
in  a  total  score  for  the  occupation.  It  would  be  still  more  desirable 
to  express  the  efficiency  in  the  form  of  a  profile,  in  which  each  com- 
ponent of  the  test,  e.g.,  ability  to  follow  instructions,  arithmetical 
ability,  ability  to  work  with  symbols,  range  of  information,  honesty, 
assurance,  etc.,  could  be  separately  reported  and  measured  against 
a  standard  or  pattern  for  any  occupation. 

Such  a  combined  measure  of  intelligence  and  character,  if  used 
for  vocational  purposes,  would  prevent  the  waste  of  high  grades  of 
intelligence  in  positions  where  it  is  not  needed  and  would  enable 


_v>>;  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

those  of  low  intelligence  to  be  located  where  their  capacity  would 
be  adequate  and  where  their  character  traits  would  make  them 
successful.  There  may  be  many  places  in  our  business  and  in- 
dustrial system  where  Fernald's  case  B  would  fit  very  well,  and 
where  an  individual  of  a  much  higher  intelligence  might  find  the 
monotony  intolerable.  To  refuse  an  occupation  in  business  and 
industry  to  all  persons  with  an  intelligence  under  seventy  per  cent, 
of  normal  without  examination  of  their  character  qualities  may 
some  time  appear  to  be  one  of  the  greatest  of  human  and  economic 
wastes.  In  the  individual  of  low  intelligence  but  stable  character 
qualities,  may  lie  a  partial  remedy  for  the  restlessness  induced  by 
extreme  specialization  and  automaticity  of  work. 

A.  T.  POFFENBERGER. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


TWO  correspondents,  Professors  Wilmon  H.  Sheldon  of  Yale  Uni- 
versity, and  W.  A.  Merrill  of  the  University  of  California, 
have  written  me  that  "integration"  has  nothing  to  do  with  gradior, 
as  I  assumed  it  to  have  in  my  article  ' '  The  Need  of  a  New  English 
Word  to  Express  Relation  in  Living  Nature."  (This  JOURNAL, 
August  18, 1921.)  And  since  Merrill  is  a  Latinist  by  profession,  there 
seems  nothing  for  me  to  do  but  to  admit  that  at  least  I  was  "wrongly 
advised"  as  he  considerately  puts  it.  What  makes  the  error  the 
more  troublesome  to  me  is  the  fact  that  I  do  not  remember  the 
source  of  my  advice,  nor,  so  far,  am  I  able  to  relocate  it. 

Professor  Merrill  also  informs  me  that  while  the  Latin  ferre 
sometimes  means,  as  I  stated,  bearing  in  the  sense  of  producing, 
the  producing  is  not  the  kind  I  meant.  It  never  means  producing 
in  the  sense  of  biological  reproducing,  I  understand  him  to  mean. 
It  appears,  consequently,  that  the  etymological  part  of  my  effort 
to  justify  conferentiation  as  the  new  word  of  which  our  language 
is  in  need,  was  quite  unfortunate. 

It  is,  however,  a  satisfaction  to  be  told  by  Professor  Merrill  that 
he  sees  no  objection  to  the  word  I  propose  if  I  think  it  is  needed ; 
for,  he  says,  "The  etymology  is  of  no  importance,  as  no  one  thinks 
of  an  automobile  as  a  self -mover. ' ' 

Perhaps,  then,  I  ought  to  be  sorry  that  in  this  instance  I  did 
not  follow,  as  according  to  my  rule  I  should  have  done,  the  familiar 
advice  Mr.  Lincoln  is  said  to  have  given  in  a  lecture  to  law  students : 
Never  try  to  prove  anything  you  do  not  have  to,  because  you  may 
thereby  be  driven  into  trying  to  prove  something  you  can't. 

But  there  is  an  aspect  of  the  use  of  words  which  goes  much  deeper 


THE  WORD  INTEGRATION  267 

than  the  question  of  the  appropriateness  of  old  words  adapted  to 
new  needs.  That  is  the  question  of  the  origin  of  new  words.  Their 
origin  I  mean,  not  in  the  linguistic  sense,  but  in  the  psycho-biological 
sense;  the  sense,  to  wit,  of  the  mental  and  physical  needs  to  which 
the  words  correspond. 

The  word  integration  illustrates  the  point  as  well  as  any  other. 
In  defining  this  word  the  dictionaries  note,  of  course,  its  relation  to 
integrare  and  then  to  integer.  And  the  verb  integrate,  it  is  usually 
mentioned,  is  related  to  the  past  participle  integratus.  Integer 
means  whole  or  undivided,  in  the  sense  of  being  untouched  or  un- 
hurt. And  integrare  means  to  renew  or  restore ;  and  the  participle 
integratus  means  renewed  or  restored. 

Now  in  order  that  a  thing  may  be  untouched  or  unhurt,  some- 
body or  something  which  might  touch  or  hurt  the  thing  is  clearly 
implied.  A  toucher  or  hurter  is  somewhere  near  by.  Likewise  a 
restoration  necessarily  implies  somebody  or  something  to  do  the 
restoring.  The  point  is  that  integration  relates  to  something  being 
done,  to  an  action — it  implies  a  doer,  an  actor. 

This  reasoning  is,  I  suppose,  about  the  same  that  a  philologist  is 
likely  to  use  in  treating  of  the  nature  of  words.  But  here  comes 
in  a  consideration  which,  though  of  great  interest  to  the  student  of 
human  psycho-biology,  does  not,  so  far  as  I  know,  appeal  greatly 
to  philologists  or  at  least  to  linguists.  I  refer  to  the  usefulness  of 
words  in  the  sense  of  biological  adaptation. 

So  far  as  I  have  noticed,  when  the  linguist  speaks  of  the  use  of 
words  he  has  in  mind  the  way  they  are  put  together  to  make  spoken 
and  written  language,  it  being  taken  for  granted  that  language  is 
the  human  way  of  expressing  ideas,  feelings,  etc.  But  to  the  modern 
biological  naturalist,  that  is  to  say  the  naturalist  whose  hold  upon 
the  present-day  conception  of  the  nature  and  origin  of  the  living 
world  reaches  clear  through  and  all  around  the  conception,  words 
are  among  the  innumerable  agencies  devised  by  the  human  creature 
to  aid  him  in  his  stupendous  task  of  maintaining  himself  upon  the 
earth  in  progress  and  happiness.  Words,  and  especially  written 
words,  are  vital  utilities  to  man,  just  as  nests  are  vital  utilities  to 
birds.  But  just  wherein  is  this  utility  of  words — the  original  and 
primeval  utility,  I  mean?  In  enabling  men  the  more  securely  and 
clearly  to  fix  in  their  minds,  and  the  more  easily  to  communicate  with 
one  another,  the  ideas  engendered  in  their  minds  through  their  ex- 
periences with  nature  round  about  them.  Viewed  thus  the  verbal 
remains  of  extinct  languages  are  as  revelatory  of  the  remote  past  of 
the  human  mind  as  the  skeletal  remains  of  extinct  races  and  species 
are  of  the  remote  past  of  the  human  body. 

Now  as  to  the  facts  of  nature  upon  which  rest  the  ideas  expressed 


268  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

by  the  word  integer  and  its  kindred.  It  is  the  verbal  forms,  integrare 
and  integrate,  that  are  specially  interesting  from  the  standpoint 
of  what  I  wrote  about  in  my  article. 

Everybody  knows  to  some  extent,  but  only  the  naturalist  knows 
systematically  and  profoundly,  that  there  are  two  very  distinct 
ways  in  which  things  are  restored  or  made  whole,  these  depending 
upon  who  or  what  the  restorer  or  whole-maker  is,  and  upon  how  the 
job  is  done.  One  of  these  ways  is  that  of  man  working  with  his 
hands  under  the  guidance  of  his  mind;  the  other  is  that  of  nature 
working  with  the  innumerable  means  at  its  disposal. 

I  have  tried  in  another  place  (The  Probable  Infinity  of  Nature 
and  Life,  p.  33)  to  bring  out  this  distinction  between  the  creations 
of  nature  and  art,  in  substance  as  follows:  The  human  being  has 
two  ways  of  creating  things.  One  way  is  by  the  use  of  its  hands 
and  brain.  The  other  is  by  the  use  of  its  generative  organs.  The 
first  way  produces  statues  and  paintings  of  other  human  beings. 
The  second  produces  real  other  such  beings.  And  by  no  possibility 
can  the  one  way  be  substituted  for  the  other. 

Men  restore  automobile  tires  by  half-soling  them ;  and  they  make 
whole  pumps  and  houses  by  manufacturing  the  parts  and  then  as- 
sembling these  and  putting  them  together  properly.  Nature  re- 
stores the  humidity  of  the  atmosphere  by  bringing  into  it  in  a 
finely  divided  state,  water  from  the  sea;  and  she  makes  whole  crys- 
tals of  salt  in  saturated  solutions.  But  restoration  and  whole-mak- 
ing by  these  methods  are  far  from  all  the  methods  by  which  restora- 
tions and  whole-makings  are  accomplished.  For  nature  restores 
worn  muscles  and  brains  by  the  assimilation  of  nourishment,  and  it 
restores  branches  of  trees  and  tails  of  lizards  when  these  have  been 
lost  by  accident  or  otherwise.  Further  she  makes  whole  new  oaks 
out  of  acorns  and  whole  new  roosters  out  of  hens'  eggs. 

These  last-mentioned  ways  of  restoring  and  whole-making  biolog- 
ical naturalists  have  studied  deeply  and  broadly,  especially  during 
late  decades.  And  beyond  question  one  of  the  most  important  re- 
sults of  their  studies  has  been  to  make  more  definite  and  penetrating 
than  before  man's  perception  of  the  difference  between  living 
nature's  way  of  restoring  and  whole-making  and,  on  the  one  hand, 
not-living  nature's  way  of  doing  these  things,  and  on  the  other 
hand,  man's  way  of  doing  them. 

It  is,  apparently,  just  because  we  moderns  have  perceived  these 
differences  so  much  more  clearly  than  the  peoples  from  whom  we 
have  largely  adopted  and  adapted  our  language  perceived  them, 
that  we  find  involved  there  an  idea  requiring  for  its  expression  some 
such  newly  adapted  word  as  conferentiation. 

Professor  Merrill  makes  a  remark  in  his  letter  which  indicates, 


THE  WORD  INTEGRATION  269 

I  believe,  not  only  how  far  our  predecessors  had  gone  toward  such 
perception,  but  also  how  much  they  fell  short  of  the  distance  later 
generations  have  gone  in  the  same  direction.  ' '  The  thought  is  com- 
mon in  ancient  philosophy,"  he  writes,  "of  breaking  up  the  whole 
into  parts  and  recombining  them  into  something  else — also  whole, 
but  a  new  one.  Thus  Lucretius  (iii,  847)  says  that  if  the  matter 
of  our  bodies  were  to  be  recollected  again  it  would  mean  nothing 
because  the  chain  of  consciousness  would  be  broken. ' ' 

From  the  passage  of  The  Nature  of  Things  here  referred  to,  and 
from  others  that  could  be  pointed  out,  it  seems  to  me  clear  that  while 
Lucretius  perceived  distinctly  enough  the  uniqueness  of  living  bodies 
as  contrasted  with  the  elements  of  which  they  are  composed,  he  per- 
ceived very  dimly  if  at  all  the  essentially  transformative  processes 
involved  in  organic  genesis.  Lucretius  was,  I  think,  far  behind 
Aristotle  in  this.  But  even  Aristotle  knew,  of  course,  only  in  the 
most  crude  and  general  way,  the  commonplace  facts  with  us  moderns 
of  metabolism,  growth,  and  development. 

If  Professor  Merrill  is  right,  as  I  do  not  doubt  he  is,  in  saying 
that  ferre  has  no  reference  to  production  in  the  sense  of  organic 
genesis,  then  even  differentation  is  really  outside  the  pale  of  living 
nature  so  far  as  etymology  is  concerned.  "Arguing  from  the  Latin 
directly,"  he  says,  "I  should  say  that  differentiate  means  to  take 
apart  .  .  .  with  an  accessory  notion  of  'carrying  away.'  '  Accord- 
ing to  this  the  actor,  the  taker-apart,  would  seem  to  be  man  acting 
with  hands  and  brain.  It  would  be  man  in  his  role  as  artist  or 
artisan.  And  only  by  adaptive  modification  could  the  word  be  made 
to  express  the  diversification  which  characterizes  organic  develop- 
ment. However,  differentiation  has  been  used  and  the  use  has  be- 
come universal,  in  the  terminology  of  organic  genesis.  By  adapta- 
tive  modification  it  has  become  thoroughly  naturalized  in  the  realm 
of  living  things.  To  this  there  is  not,  as  I  understand,  the  slightest 
objection. 

By  parallel  reasoning  conferentiation  could  be  naturalized  in  the 
same  realm  to  express  the  unification  which  characterizes  organic 
development.  And  the  biological  importance  of  providing  differ- 
entiation with  its  natural  organic  mate,  is  that  the  effort  which  has 
been  widely  made  of  late  to  pair  differentiation  off  with  integration 
is  resulting  in  ideas  that  are  not  only  confused  but  are  genuinely 
harmful,  owing  to  the  fact  that  integration  is  already  bound  to  dis- 
integration as  its  natural  inorganic  mate. 

One  practical  consequence  of  the  general  employment  of  integra- 
tion in  this  inconsistent  and  inorganic  sense,  I  tried  to  bring  out  in 
my  essay.  That  consequence  is  the  deterring  effect  such  use  has 
upon  perceiving  the  real  nature  of  the  action  of  bodies  or  of  parts 


270  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  bodies  on  one  another  in  order  to  make  the  resultant  new  body 
truly  organic  or  living.  This  action  is  so  deeply  reciprocal  that 
(quoting)  "while  producing  determinative  change  in  [each  of]  the 
bodies,  at  the  same  time  [it]  leaves  the  individuality  of  these  not 
only  identifiable  and  unimpaired,  but  even  improved  relative  to  their 
former  states."  The  sentence  from  which  this  is  quoted  begins  "It 
is  that  relational  action  in  living  bodies  which,  while  producing" 
etc.  (as  above). 

It  now  seems  to  me  that  instead  of  conceiving  this  "relational 
action"  as  operating  "m  living  bodies,"  as  though  it  were  merely 
an  incident  to  such  bodies,  we  must  conceive  it  to  be  of  the  very 
deepest  nature  of  these  bodies.  Except  for  this  peculiar  reciprocal 
action  apparently  no  body  could  possess  any  of  the  attributes  of  life. 

I  wish  now  to  invite  attention  to  another  injurious  effect  almost 
sure  to  result  from  a  general  use  of  integration  as  the  linguistic  mate 
of  differentiation.  Since  integration  has  long  been  generally  ac- 
cepted as  the  antithetic  mate  of  disintegration,  the  common  utiliza- 
tion of  it  in  the  terminology  of  human  affairs  would  almost  inevi- 
tably tend  to  set  it  in  opposition  to  differentiation  in  the  sense  of 
inhibiting  it.  Or,  otherwise  stated,  since  all  differentiation  involves 
change,  the  tendency  would  be  to  make  the  principle  of  integration 
act  as  an  inhibitor  of  any  change.  With  the  conservative  type  of 
mind,  the  idea  of  integration  could  easily  become  a  new  and  power- 
ful brake  upon  the  wheels  of  human  progress,  since  it  would  be  the 
most  natural  thing  in  the  world  Jfor  such  minds  to  believe  any 
change  whatever  that  did  not  chance  to  be  to  their  personal  liking, 
to  portend  disintegration  rather  than  progress. 

WILLIAM  E.  RITTER. 

LA  JOLLA,  CALIFORNIA. 

BOOK  REVIEWS 

Russian  Dissenters.    FREDERICK  C.  CONYBEARE.     Cambridge:  Har- 
vard University  Press.    1921.    Pp.  370. 

Perhaps  no  group  of  Christian  believers  are  more  deserving  of 
study  for  their  psychology  and  their  rites  than  are  the  Russian  dis- 
senters. Few  indeed  are  the  religions  of  Western  Europe  or  America 
that  are  as  picturesque  or  as  removed  from  the  common  thought  of 
the  world.  Yet  it  may  be  added  that  few  considerable  numbers  of 
Christians  have  ever  received  less  attention  at  home  or  abroad. 
Hitherto  in  English  the  chief  source  has  been  the  descriptive  account 
of  them  in  M.  Leroy-Beaulieu 's  Empire  of  the  Tsars  and  Russians, 
and  for  this  reason  we  welcome  the  closely  historical  treatment  of 
Professor  Conybeare. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  271 

Although  the  author  modestly  states  that  his  work  is  a  compila- 
tion, yet  we  can  not  help  feeling  that  his  knowledge  of  Bogomilism 
and  the  allied  cults  has  enabled  him  to  present  admirably  the  strik- 
ing similarities  between  these  and  the  Kussian  sectarians.  It  is  the 
more  remarkable,  therefore,  that  the  book  does  not  discuss  the  pos- 
sible direct  contacts  between  Russia  and  the  Bogomils  in  the  early 
centuries  and  the  first  organized  antiecclesiastical  organization  of 
Eussia,  the  sect  of  the  Strigolniks  which  appeared  in  Pskov  in  the 
fourteenth  century.  Similarly  we  miss  any  description  of  the 
Judaizers,  who  were  able  to  place  on  the  metropolitan  see  of  Holy 
Russia  in  1493  a  man  who  was  almost  a  convert  to  the  Jewish  faith. 
We  should  also  like  to  know  the  opinion  of  Professor  Conybeare  on 
the  Armenian  Martin  whom  later  stories  (probably  apocryphal)  re- 
garded as  the  originator  of  the  rites  of  the  Old  Believers. 

Unfortunately  the  righteous  indignation  of  the  author  at  the 
stupid  and  tyrannical  government  of  the  Tsar  has  led  him  to  be 
unjust  to  the  Orthodox  Church.  He  rightly  emphasizes  the  dislike 
and  the  dismay  with  which  the  peasants  greeted  the  centralizing  policy 
of  Moscow.  He  does  not  emphasize  the  cause  of  that  policy.  To  him 
the  Tartar  invasion  means  that  a  savage  people  had  wiped  from  the 
earth  a  peaceful  and  developing  native  civilization  (p.  26).  This 
has  been  a  popular  idea  since  the  World  War  and  the  Russian  Rev- 
olution. Centuries  of  bloody  Civil  War  in  Russia  which  culminated 
in  the  sack  of  Kiev  in  1169  and  the  accounts  of  the  old  Russian  slave 
trade  luridly  deny  that  the  source  of  all  evil  lay  in  the  autocracy. 
It  may  well  be  argued  that  it  was  only  the  policy  of  autocracy, 
bribery  and  servility  inaugurated  by  Moscow  with  the  blessing  of 
the  Church  that  succeeded  in  unifying  Russia  and  saving  Moscow 
from  that  permanent  foreign  control  which  ruined  Kievan  Russia 
for  centuries.  The  Troublous  Times  and  the  occupation  of  the 
Kremlin  by  Poland  in  1610  again  brought  Russia  to  the  verge  of 
ruin  and  rendered  necessary  the  changes  of  the  century,  although 
the  unhappy  country  did  not  have  the  trained  leaders  to  undertake 
the  work. 

In  the  rough  manner  of  his  time  Nikon  endeavored  to  carry  out 
needed  reforms.  If  we  read  the  virulent  denunciation  of  the  Pa- 
triarch on  p.  19  and  the  criticism  of  his  reforms  on  p.  42,  we  notice 
a  contrast.  Nikon  fought  to  free  the  clergy  from  a  humiliating  posi- 
tion as  the  slave  of  the  mir.  He  fought  against  a  narrow  nationalism 
which  hated  the  Latins,  loathed  the  Kievan  monks  and  despised  the 
Greeks.  Awakum  and  his  followers  were  far  less  concerned  that 
Nikon  used  a  poor  Greek  manuscript  than  that  he  used  a  Greek 
manuscript  at  all.  One  of  the  chief  problems  was  the  decrees  of  the 


272  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Stoglav  Council.  This  supported  the  contention  of  the  nationalists, 
but  is  it  "monstrously  critical"  for  the  Orthodox  to  doubt  the 
validity  of  decrees  passed  in  1551  and  invoked  for  the  first  time  in 
1642  f  The  innovations  of  the  Old  Believers  probably  arose  in  the 
fifteenth  and  sixteenth  centuries.  It  is  hard  to  see  how  they  could 
have  originated  during  the  period  when  all  the  higher  ecclesiastics 
were  themselves  Greek,  and  the  Church  was  absolutely  an  exotic 
growth  (p.  3). 

The  same  unwillingness  to  recognize  anything  but  might  as  on  the 
side  of  the  Orthodox  is  a  sad  blemish  on  the  entire  work.  The 
"jaundiced  narrative"  of  Ivanovski  (p.  115)  denies  the  moral  ex- 
cellences of  the  thief  and  forger  Bishop  Epiphanius.  The  four 
bishops  who  succeeded  him  were  so  obviously  of  an  unsatisfactory 
character  that  the  author  forbears  to  mention  them. 

The  author  has  gone  too  far  in  his  endeavor  to  deny  or  defend 
suicide  by  fire.  The  teachings  of  Avvakum  (quoted  in  Anderson, 
Raskol  and  the  Sects,  p.  130)  recommend  it.  The  stikh  of  the 
Woman  Alleluia  ascribed  this  teaching  to  Christ  himself  (Porfirev, 
History  of  Russian  Literature,  Vol.  I,  p.  355).  Finally  M.  Leroy- 
Beaulieu  cites  a  number  of  modern  instances  (op.  cit.,  Vol.  Ill,  p.  320). 
It  would  be  interesting  to  explain  the  purpose  of  Ivanov  in  starting 
one  holocaust  after  another  (p.  154).  It  is  more  reasonable  to 
assume  that  he  was  seeking  to  make  martyrs  of  his  disciples  or  dupes. 

The  chapter  on  marriage  is  very  full  but  again  the  author's 
enthusiasm  for  the  sectarians  leads  him  to  veil  in  many  words  what 
may  seem  to  be  an  unpleasant  condition.  The  key  to  the  entire 
question  is  to  be  found  on  p.  193.  "The  'marriageless'  sectary  may 
not  approve  of  unions  concluded  for  the  whole  of  life,  but  find  it  a 
burden.  He  aspires  to  another  type  of  conjugal  relationship,  a  type 
which  more  nearly  approximates  to  the  ancient  Slavonic  free  union, 
dissoluble  by  the  will  of  either  party.  He  has  scanty  regard  for  the 
Byzantine  type  of  family  which  has  only  gained  currency  in  Russia 
during  the  last  few  centuries."  Nestor  and  the  early  chroniclers 
declared  that  the  early  pagan  Slavs  practised  free  love  and  had  no 
conception  of  family  life.  The  Orthodox  sacrament  of  matrimony 
and  the  life-long  monogamy  seem  to  have  been  inseparably  connected 
in  the  minds  of  the  Russians  and  the  loss  of  one  necessarily  destroyed 
the  other.  Certain  of  the  sectarians  were  able  to  develop  the  old- 
fashioned  Protestant  conception  of  marriage  and  were  able  to  bring 
order  into  their  life.  Others  endeavored  to  satisfy  their  consciences 
in  various  ways  and  we  learn  that  many  of  the  Raskol  were  living  in 
relationships  which  even  their  own  code  would  not  approve  (p.  209). 
These  relationships  were  tolerated  and  we  need  only  mention  the 


BOOK  REVIEWS  273 

demoralizing  influence  of  such  manners.  What  part  does  this  play 
in  the  rumors  of  various  marriage  innovations  since  the  Russian 
Eevolution  ? 

Turning  to  the  second  part  of  the  work,  we  note  with  regret  that 
Professor  Conybeare  did  not  make  use  of  the  recent  work  of  Bonch- 
Bruyevich,  Materials  for  the  History  and  Study  of  the  Russian  Sects 
and  RaskoL  In  this  there  is  published  a  large  collection  of  the  songs 
of  the  Dukhobortsy.  We  may  add  that  many  of  the  scholars  of 
Russian  religion,  such  as  Vladimir  Anderson,  group  the  Dukhobortsy 
together  with  the  Khlysty,  and  many  of  their  documents,  edited  by 
Bonch-Bruyevich,  testify  to  their  belief  in  this  similarity.  They  are 
certainly  more  closely  related  than  are  the  Dukhobortsy  and  the 
Stundists.  Finally  Professor  Conybeare  does  not  mention  the  spirit- 
ual dynasty  of  the  Dukhobortsy,  one  of  their  chief  characteristics. 
Aylmer  Maude  in  his  work,  A  Peculiar  People,  describes  in  detail  the 
via  dolorosa  leading  to  the  emigration  to  Canada.  He  also  reveals 
his  disgust  at  the  trickery  of  Tchertkoff  and  the  leaders  of  the  Dukh- 
obortsy toward  those  who  were  helping  the  poor  Russians.  This 
omission  relieves  the  author  of  mentioning  the  naked  pilgrimages  and 
other  events1  which  present  the  "true  soul  of  the  Russian  peasant" 
in  a  less  favorable  light. 

The  account  of  the  Mystical  Sects  could  also  be  improved  by  the 
use  of  the  work  of  Bonch-Bruyevich.  Their  denial  of  the  unique  deity 
of  Christ  gains  for  them  a  certain  amount  of  approval,  though  we 
should  like  to  hear  more  of  the  succession  of  Christs  among  them. 
Professor  Conybeare  mildly  remarks  that  some  of  their  Christs  may 
impose  upon  their  followers  (p.  343),  but  he  really  disapproves  of 
no  sectarian  save  the  "obscene  fanatic"  Selivanov.  This  man  was 
once  a  member  of  the  Khlysty  or  "People  of  God"  as  they  prefer 
to  be  called,  and  the  violence  of  the  Skoptsy  can  easily  be  interpreted 
as  a  reaction  from  unrestrained  license  in  the  parent  sect.  In  this 
connection  we  may  mention  the  career  of  Shchetinin.  This  man 
(the  subject  of  a  long  study  by  Bonch-Bruyevich)  founded  the  sect 
of  the  Chemreki,  which  was  an  acknowledged  branch  of  the  Khlyst 
movement.  He  openly  preached  religious  immorality  and  main- 
tained his  position  for  some  years.  There  have  been  many  similar 
teachers,  notably  the  famous  Rasputin,  who  operated  in  Russian  court 
circles.  Apologists  for  the  sectarians  have  usually  denied  that  these 
men  represented  any  element  of  the  Khlysty,  but  in  such  a  case  they 
should  group  them  as  representative  of  a  certain  tendency  perhaps 
connected  with  the  Slavonic  free  union. 

i  The  most  recent  of  these  was  a  threat  by  the  God-man,  Peter  Verigin,  to 
kill  all  the  children  of  the  community  as  a  protest  agadnst  the  Canadian  govern- 
ment. (New  York  Times,  February  21,  1922.) 


274  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

The  author  again  has  not  sufficiently  emphasized  the  importance 
which  mystic  anarchy  has  had  on  the  entire  movement.  Most  of  the 
sects  which  have  been  opposed  to  the  government  of  the  Tsar  were 
opposed  not  because  it  was  autocratic,  but  because  it  was  a  govern- 
ment. The  refusal  of  military  service,  the  refusal  of  the  oath  of 
allegiance,  the  refusal  to  pay  taxes,  all  recur  with  monotonous  regu- 
larity in  the  accounts  of  these  sects.  The  World  War  brought  them 
to  the  attention  of  this  Government  (see  the  article  of  Dean  Stone 
in  the  Columbia  University  Quarterly,  Vol.  XXI,  p.  263).  Their 
opposition  to  secular  government  does  not  render  them  opposed  to 
autocratic  rule  by  their  Christ-ruler,  and  in  the  course  of  time  it  will 
probably  be  seen  that  these  sects  are  less  of  a  trouble  in  an  autocracy 
than  in  any  form  of  democracy. 

We  may  well  compare  the  Russian  sectarian  movements  to  a  sea 
with  certain  main  currents.  On  the  surface  of  these  currents  are 
various  waves  which  rise  and  fall  in  constant  changing  struggle. 
These  waves  are  the  individual  sects.  None  of  them  has  ever  formu- 
lated any  definite  code;  none  of  them,  save  the  Austrian  Hierarchy 
of  the  Popovtsy,  has  maintained  a  clear  and  distinct  history  similar 
to  that  of  the  leading  Protestant  sects  of  Western  Europe.  Most  of 
them  form  sympathetic  but  disorganized  groups  with  no  external 
discipline  and  any  movement  is  liable  in  different  places  to  produce 
all  types  of  leaders,  from  the  pious  efficiency  of  Denisov  to  the 
savagery  of  Selivanov.  For  this  reason  it  is  as  impossible  to  approve 
their  principles  as  a  movement  as  it  is  to  condemn  their  excesses  as 
a  sign  of  general  decadence. 

In  conclusion  we  may  say  that  the  book  would  have  been  far 
more  valuable  had  the  author  not  been  so  animated  with  the  belief 
that  it  is  "the  heretics  and  dissenters  [of  both  hemispheres]  who 
will  point  the  way  [to  unity]  and  by  their  example  shame  formalists 
into  true  charity"  (p.  258).  He  has  brought  together  a  great  mass 
of  valuable  material,  but  his  constant  tendency  to  champion  the  cause 
of  the  dissenter  and  to  omit  or  deny  any  aspects  which  do  not  preju- 
dice us  in  his  favor  weakens  the  book.  The  reader  should  most 
certainly  supplement  this  work  with  that  of  M.  Leroy-Beaulieu,  who 
has  described  the  defects  of  the  Orthodox  Church  of  Russia  no  less 
severely,  but  has  endeavored  at  the  same  time  to  write  impartially 
of  the  different  sectarian  movements  and  to  evaluate  their  real  signi- 
ficance for  Russia  and  civilization. 

CLARENCE  AUGUSTUS  MANNING. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVEHSITT. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  275 

Bibliotheca  Chemico-Mathematica :  A  Catalogue  of  works  in  many 

tongues  on  Exact  and  Applied  Science,  With  a  Subject  Index. 

Compiled  and  annotated  by  H.  Z.  and  H.  C.  S.    2  Vols.    London : 

Henry  Sotheran  and  Co.    1921.    Pp.  964. 

These  two  volumes  are  made  up  of  three  booksellers'  catalogues 
and  an  index.  They  form,  however,  one  of  the  most  available  bibli- 
ographies of  the  history  of  miodern  science.  In  each  of  the  three 
catalogues  the  authors  are  arranged  in  alphabetic  order,  and  natur- 
ally a  great  many  of  the  books  entered  are  of  little  general  interest. 
But  the  full  and  elaborate  index,  giving  also  the  dates  of  the  differ- 
ent works  referred  to,  is  a  highly  useful  key  to  any  one  interested 
in  the  history  of  science.  As  is  to  be  expected  under  the  circum- 
stances, the  collection  is  very  uneven  as  regards  completeness.  Thus 
there  are  no  entries  on  Brownian  movement,  on  the  theory  of  quanta 
or  on  the  algebra  of  logic,  and  almost  nothing  on  statistical  methods. 
Even  when  the  bibliography  is  rather  full  as  in  theoretic  physics,  some 
of  the  very  great  and  epoch-making  treatises,  like  that  of  Bocovich 
which  united  the  work  of  Newton  and  Leibniz,  are  missing.  On  other 
topics,  however,  such  as  the  history  of  alchemy,  the  modern  theory 
of  solutions,  or  the  history  and  theory  of  electricity,  the  lists  are 
more  adequate. 

The  many  annotations  to  the  titles,  giving  biographic  and 
historical  information,  are  as  a  rule  rather  interesting  and  lively. 
' '  The  pioneers  of  science  have  never  been  of  the  dry  as  dust  order. ' ' 
Students  of  philosophy  may  be  surprised  to  learn  that  the  com- 
mon sense  realism  of  Reid  was  originated  by  D.  Abercrombie  's  Acade- 
mia  Scientarum  or  History  of  Natural  Sciences,  1687 ;  and  it  is  in- 
structive to  learn  that  the  authorship  of  a  book  on  the  Varieties  and 
Uncertainties  of  Aries  and  Sciences  landed  Agrippa  von  Nettesheim 
in  prison.  As  these  annotations  are  generally  based  on  secondary 
sources,  some  of  them  are  rather  misleading.  Thus  it  is  not  true 
that  the  phlogiston  theory  retarded  the  progress  of  science.  Like 
other  false  hypotheses  it  led  to  a  great  deal  of  new  investigation  and 
hence  to  the  progress  of  science. 

Perhaps  the  most  interesting  feature  of  these  two  volumes  is  the 
large  number  of  plates  giving  portraits  of  the  greatest  of  the  scien- 
tists and  facsimiles  of  the  actual  texts  of  the  older  books.  The  most 
cursory  examination  of  these  illustrations  will  give  one  an  extraordi- 
narily vivid  sense  of  the  intellectual  vitality  of  previous  centuries, 
and  dispell  the  fashionable  but  foolish  idea  that  before  Darwin 
or  Newton  the  world  dwelt  in  utter  scientific  darkness. 

The  annotators,  H.  Zeitlinger  and  H.  C.  Sotheran,  have  not  al- 
ways made  the  most  of  their  opportunities.  I  am  tempted  to  give 
two  instances.  Colenso's  Algebra  is  entered  without  noting  that  it 


276  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY 

is  by  the  same  Bishop  Colenso  who  upset  the  old  biblical  theology 
in  England  by  his  book  on  the  Pentateuch  in  which  his  mathematical 
reasoning  created  great  distress  for  those  who  regarded  every  story 
in  the  Bible  as  literally  true.  Colenso  thus  lost  his  bishopric  on 
account  of  his  mathematical  proclivities.  The  second  case  is  the 
entry  of  W.  Carpenter's  pamphlet  on,  Water  not  Convex,  the  Earth 
not  a  Globe,  1871.  This  is  part  of  a  famous  law-suit.  A  wager  hav- 
ing been  made  that  the  convexity  of  the  earth  could  not  be  proved, 
Alfred  Russell  Wallace  proceeded  to  do  so  with  optical  instruments 
on  the  water-level  of  a  canal.  The  loser  of  the  wager,  however,  re- 
fused to  pay  the  bet.  W.  Carpenter  was  the  dissenting  referee,  and 
his  pamphlet  illustrates  how  hard  it  is  for  experimental  evidence  to 
prevail  over  general  convictions. 

MORRIS  R.  COHEN. 
COLLEGE  or  THE  CITY  or  NEW  YORK. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

JOURNAL  OF  EDUCATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY.  September, 
1921.  An  Experimental  and  Statistical  Study  of  Reading  and  Read- 
ing Tests:  ARTHUR  I.  GATES  (303-314). -First  of  three  installments. 
Conclusions  and  summary  in  the  November  issue.  Constancy  of  the 
Stanford-Binet  I.  Q.  as  shown  by  Retests:  HAROLD  RUOG  and  CECILE 
COLLOTON  (315-322). -An  examination  of  the  reports  of  Terman, 
Cuneo,  Garrison,  Poull,  Wallin,  Fermon  and  Stenquist  was  made. 
The  conclusion  drawn  is  that  "much  confidence  can  be  put  on  a 
single  I.  Q.  if  the  examination  is  made  by  experienced  and  well- 
trained  examiners  who  use  rigorously  the  standardized  procedure  for 
giving  the  test. ' '  Recent  studies,  except  those  of  Fermon  and  Sten- 
quist, closely  confirm  Terman  in  his  earlier  statements.  The  com- 
parison of  the  findings  of  Fermon  and  Stenquist  with  those  of  other 
studies  throws  great  doubt  on  the  validity  of  the  examining  which 
was  done  by  their  workers.  Constancy  of  I.  Q.  in  Mental  Defectives, 
according  to  the  Stanford  Revision  of  Binet  Tests:  LOUISE  E.  POULL 
(323-324). -126  inmates  of  the  Children's  Hospital  on  Randall's 
Island,  New  York  City,  were  retested.  The  interval  between  the 
first  and  second  tests  varied  from  six  months  to  three  years;  age 
of  subjects  from  4  to  28  years ;  the  I.  Q.  of  the  first  test  varied  from 
20  to  90.  The  subjects  as  a  group  did  not  deteriorate,  the  average 
change  was  an  increase  of  -f  1.28.  The  question  of  the  constancy 
of  I.  Q.  is  not  settled.  A  large  percentage  of  the  cases  shows  varia- 
tions which  operate  to  change  the  classification  and  in  cases  above  the 
obvious  imbecile  type,  only  observation  and  retesting  can  discover 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  277 

the  individuals  who  require  permanent  supervision  or  institutional 
care.  Mental  growth  and  the  I.  Q.:  LEWIS  M.  TERMAN  (325-341).- 
The  work  of  Dr.  Doll  is  examined.  "His  own  conclusions  are  so  often 
either  contrary  to  his  facts  or  else  irrelevant  to  them  that  verification 
is  always  necessary. ' '  The  article  is  continued  in  the  October  issue. 
Department  for  Discussion  of  Research  Problems.  Notes  on  Articles 
in  Educational  Psychology  in  Current  issues  of  other  Magazines. 
Special  Review  of  Mrs.  Burgess's  Monograph  on  Silent  Reading. 
New  Publications  in  Educational  Psychology  and  Related  Fields 
of  Education. 

Root,  William  T.,  Jr.  A  Socio-Psychological  Study  of  Fifty-three 
Supernormal  Children.  (Psychological  Monographs,  Vol.  XXIX, 
No.  4.)  Princeton,  N.  J. :  Psychological  Review  Co.  1921.  Pp. 
134. 

Spiller,  G.  A  New  System  of  Scientific  Procedure :  Being  an  Attempt 
to  Ascertain,  Develop,  and  Systematise  the  General  Methods 
Employed  in  Modern  Enquiries  at  Their  Best.  London:  Watts 
&Co.  1921.  Pp.441. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

To  the  Members  of  the  American  Philosophical  Association,  Eastern 
Division: 

At  its  Annual  Meeting,  December  30,  1921,  the  American  Philo- 
sophical Association  (Eastern  Division)  appropriated  a  considerable 
part  of  its  available  funds  for  literary  aid  to  European  universities 
and  scholars.  The  vote  on  the  resolution  was  unanimous.  The  great 
need  for  books  and  journals  on  the  part  of  foreign  scholars  impov- 
erished by  the  war  and  its  consequences  impressed  the  Association 
when  it  was  brought  to  the  attention  of  the  Meeting.  From  the 
editors  among  its  membership  it  learned  also  of  the  many  requests 
from  abroad  for  gifts  of  current  journals — requests  which  the 
several  reviews  have  often  met,  but  which  as  a  whole  their  resources 
do  not  allow  them  to  satisfy.  Finally,  it  was  felt  that  this  was  a 
form  of  international  cooperation  which  all  could  approve. 

The  Association  appropriated  two  hundred  dollars — one  third  of 
its  balance — for  this  purpose.  In  the  discussion  of  the  motion,  the 
hope  was  also  expressed  that  additional  gifts  of  money  or  books 
might  be  received  from  individuals.  The  management  of  the  fund 
was  entrusted  to  the  Committee  on  International  Cooperation,  which 
met  immediately  and  appointed  Professors  Woodbridge  and  Cohen 
a  sub-committee  to  take  direct  charge  of  the  work.  Arrangements 


278  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

have  now  been  perfected  for  the  forwarding  and  distribution,  with- 
out cost,  of  whatever  we  may  be  able  to  give.  It  is  very  desirable 
that  any  of  our  members  who  feel  able  to  contribute,  or  to  spare 
books  or  journals  from  their  libraries,  should  communicate  with  the 
sub-committee  so  soon  as  may  be  convenient.  In  particular,  it  is 
desired  to  collect  works  representative  of  the  more  recent  phases  of 
American  thought.  In  case  of  doubt,  the  sub-committee  will  be 
glad  to  answer  concerning  the  suitableness  of  any  suggested  dona- 
tions. Checks  may  be  drawn,  and  books  forwarded  to  Professor 
Frederick  J.  E.  Woodbridge,  Columbia  University,  New  York  City, 
New  York. 

A.  C.  ARMSTRONG,  Chairman, 
FREDERICK  J.  E.  WOODBRIDGE, 
MORRIS  R.  COHEN. 

To  the  Editors  of  the  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY  : 

In  the  interest  of  the  freedom  of  discussion  so  essential  to  philos- 
ophy, I  wish  to  protest  most  respectfully  against  the  position  of 
Dr.  Parkhurst's  animadversions  on  the  paper  I  read  before  the 
American  Philosophical  Association.  To  question  the  evidence  for 
that  which  is  generally  taken  for  granted  is  surely  one  of  the  func- 
tions of  a  philosopher,  and  this  I  tried  to  do  to  the  best  of  my  ability 
in  reference  to  the  popular  belief  in  universal  evolution,  in  the  sub- 
conscious mind,  and  in  induction  as  the  essence  of  scientific  method 
(I  was  very  careful  to  discriminate,  as  Dr.  Parkhurst  does  not,  be- 
tween universal  evolution  and  Darwinian  natural  selection).  If 
my  questionings  are  based  on  ignorance  or  misapprehension,  Dr. 
Parkhurst  and  other  friends  of  these  doctrines  can  readily  correct  me 
and  thus  render  a  great  service  to  science  by  guarding  others  against 
similar  errors.  But  to  ignore  my  actual  arguments  and  to  deplore 
them  "chiefly  for  the  improper  use  to  which  they  might  be  put"  by 
obscurantists  in  Kentucky  or  in  a  New  York  newspaper,  seems  to 
me  to  introduce  or  revive  a  most  unwarranted  and  dangerous  res- 
traint on  the  freedom  of  philosophic  discussion.  Surely  the  danger 
from  misuse  by  temporarily  popular  obscurantists  (and  what  utter- 
ance of  man  is  guaranteed  against  such  misuse?)  is  much  less  serious 
than  the  danger  from  philosophers  suppressing  their  opinions,  even 
before  their  colleagues,  lest  obscurantists  misuse  such  expression. 
Would  not  such  a  policy  be  itself  literally  the  veriest  obscurantism? 

Similarly,  because  philosophy  has  nothing  to  gain  by  introducing 
into  its  discussions  the  passionate  intolerances  of  the  marketplace, 
it  seems  to  me  unfortunate  to  have  philosophic  papers  characterized 
in  moral  terms  such  as  "cynical,"  etc.  In  view  of  the  uncontradicted 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  279 

agreement  (expressed  by  Prof.  Pratt)  which  my  paper  received  at 
its  reading,  a  reasonable  respect  for  our  fellow-philosophers'  power 
to  express  their  dissent  makes  it  doubful  whether  many  besides  Dr. 
Parkhurst  felt  a  disapproval  so  intense  that  "nothing  short  of  a 
pitched  battle  would  have  promised  satisfaction."  But  in  any  case 
the  interest  of  philosophic  clarity  would  have  been  better  served  by 
refuting  rather  than  merely  condemning  my  contentions. 

Finally,  Dr.  Parkhurst  sets  up  the  authority  of  Prof.  Bateson. 
Bateson  is  undoubtedly  a  great  authority  on  biologic  variation,  but 
not  on  philosophic  discussion.  In  any  case  I  may  retort  that  it  is 
possible  to  have  faith  in  experimental  science  and  have  little  use  for 
the  concept  of  evolution — witness  the  work  of  our  leading  experi- 
mental biologist,  Jacques  Loeb,  whose  condemnation  of  the  scientific 
use  of  the  concept  of  evolution  is  much  more  drastic  than  anything  I 
ventured  to  say.  I  might  similarly  cite  the  position  of  our  leading 
anthropologist,  Professor  Boas,  with  reference  to  social  evolution. 

It  is  too  bad  that  we  live  in  a  world  in  which  the  advanced  scien- 
tific thought  of  sixty  years  ago  has  not  yet  penetrated  to  some  of 
the  multitude.  But  we  must  not  suddenly  become  panicky  on  ac- 
count of  this,  and  limit  our  own  freedom  of  thought  and  expression 
and  prevent  intellectual  progress.  Whatever  the  Mosaic  cosmology 
may  be  to  the  multitude,  it  is  undoubtedly  a  mjyth  to  most  philos- 
ophers. But  the  refusal  of  philosophers  to  recognize  the  mythical 
character  of  popular  doctrine  of  universal  evolution,  has  led  to 
unjustifiable  dogmatism  by  dulling  the  critical  edge  of  the  sense 
for  evidence.  Dr.  Parkhurst  may  call  this  view  skepticism  or  even 
obscurantism,  but  I  see  no  reason  for  making  it  esoteric. 

Respectfully  yours, 

MORRIS  E.  COHEN 

The  New  York  Branch  of  the  American  Psychological  Associa- 
tion met  on  Monday,  April  24,  in  Schermerhorn  Hall,  Columbia 
University.  The  following  papers  were  read : 

Dr.  F.  Lyman  Wells :  A  Method  of  Memory  Examination  adapted 
to  Psychotic  Cases. 

Dr.  Beardsley  Ruml:  Notes  on  Applied  Psychology. 

Dr.  Clara  F.  Chassell:  A  Test  of  Ability  to  Weigh  Foreseen 
Social  Consequences. 

A  meeting  of  the  Aristotelian  Society  was  held  on  March  20, 
1922,  Professor  G.  Dawes  Hicks  in  the  Chair.  Professor  R.  F.  A. 
Hoernle  read  a  paper  on  "Some  Byways  of  the  Theory  of  Knowl- 
edge," a  synopsis  of  which  follows: 


280  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

In  the  attempt  to  give  scientific  precision  to  their  language, 
some  philosophers  have  introduced  into  the  theory  of  knowledge 
a  new  distinction,  viz.,  the  distinction  between  first-hand  knowl- 
edge and  second-hand  knowledge  (or  knowledge  mediated  by  sym- 
bols), alongside  of  the  current  distinctions  between  "knowledge 
by  acquaintance"  and  "knowledge  by  description,"  or  "immediate 
acquaintance"  and  "thought."  Acquaintance  and  immediate 
of  language  and  of  analysis,  whereas  first-hand  knowledge  (e.g.,  that 
experience  are,  in  current  theory,  commonly  characterized  by  absence 
of  a  botanist  engaged  in  research)  may  involve  any  amount  of 
analysis  and  symbols  of  all  sorts.  Yet  there  will  be  no  divorce  of 
description  from  acquaintance,  or  of  thought  from  immediate  data, 
but  the  data  will  be  ordered  and  will  acquire  significance,  and  their 
meaning  will  come  to  the  investigator  as  fulfilled  and  realized  in 
a  sense  in  which  it  can  not  do  to  one  who  merely  reads  his  account 
at  second-hand.  The  choice  of  terminology  is  no  mere  matter  of 
words,  for  it  is  a  choice  of  meanings,  and  therefore  of  the  qualities 
and  relations  which  we  affirm  as  "true"  and  "real"  of  the  object 
under  discussion.  Definition  does  not  help,  for  it  leaves  open  the 
question  whether  anything  bearing  the  character  defined  exists. 
The  suggestion  was  made  that  a  comparative  and  systematic  study 
of  philosophical  languages  is  much  to  be  desired,  as  a  preliminary  to 
rational  choice,  and,  in  any  case,  as  a  help  to  better  mutual  under- 
standing. 


VOL.  XIX,  No.  11  MAY  25,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


ME.  RUSSELL'S  PSYCHOLOGY 

discussion  of  certain  points  in  Mr.  Russell's  Analysis  of 
•*"  Mind  is  animated  by  no  hostile  spirit.  I  fully  recognize  that 
criticism  of  a  view  with  which  one  has  nothing  in  common  is  likely 
to  lead  to  nothing  but  an  unprofitable  wrangle ;  but  I  seem,  to  my- 
self at  least,  to  possess  many  vital  points  of  agreement  with  Mr. 
Russell. 

1.  We  are  agreed,  I  think,  that  philosophies  should  be,  and  are, 
experiments  with  life,  and  both  hold  our  own  in  this  experimental 
spirit. 

2.  We  are  both,  in  consequence,  willing  to  learn  from  experience 
in  the  widest  sense,  and  in  every  possible  way. 

3.  I  recognize  in  Mr.  Russell,  not  only  a  writer  whom  it  is  always 
a  pleasure  and  a  profit  to  read,  but  also  a  philosopher  who  is  emi- 
nently clear-headed  and  honest — both  of  them  qualities  which  are 
by  no  means  as  common  as  it  is  polite  to  suppose.     To  discuss  a 
philosopher  who  plays  with  his  cards  on  the  table  and  scorns  to  keep 
an  additional  set  of  trumps  up  his  sleeve,  and  moreover  plays  them 
for  all  they  are  worth,  can  not  but  yield  a  good  game,  clarifying 
and  instructive,  in  which  the  victory  may  be  disputed  to  the  end. 

4.  The  Analysis  of  Mind  is  to  me  a  most  welcome  recognition 
of  the  need  every  serious  philosophy  should  feel  of  coming  to  terms 
with  psychology.     So  long  as  this  need  is  not  recognized,  the  present 
miserable  state  of  the  philosophic  sciences  seems  bound  to  continue. 
Our  logics  must  continue  to  be  meaningless,  our  ethics  and  esthetics 
to  be  nullities,  our  metaphysics  to  be  phantasies  of  personal  idiosyn- 
crasy, our  psychologies  to  be  servile  and  futile  imitations  of  natural 
sciences,  while  the  whole  strength  of  philosophy  is  dissipated  in 
intestine  discords.    The  philosophic  sciences,  like  the  nations,  must 
learn  to  cooperate,  or  perish. 

But  to  cooperate  they  must  be  willing  to  make  concessions  on 
both  sides,  and  explore  every  possibility  of  success,  however  novel 
and  repulsive  it  may  seem  to  our  innate  conservatism.  It  is  no  argu- 
ment against  Behaviorism  or  Psychoanalysis  or  Psychical  Research 
that  they  shock  our  prejudices. 

For  this  reason  I  can  not  resent  even  the  parts  of  Mr.  Russell's 
analysis  which  I  most  dissent  from,  and  shall  select  for  special  con- 

281 


282  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

sideration  in  preference  to  the  far  more  extensive  portions  of  which 
I  admire  the  substance  as  well  as  the  form.  I  take  no  exception  to 
his  penchant  for  Behaviorism,  which  he  has,  very  candidly,  set  down 
in  part  to  personal  bias  in  this  very  JOURNAL.  (Vol.  XVI,  No.  1). 
I  am  quite  willing  to  grant  that  if  Behaviorism  can  be  shown  to  work, 
even  as  a  method,  it  corroborates  thereby  its  claim  to  truth :  only  its 
advocates  should  endeavor  to  show  also  that  it  works  better  than  any 
extant  alternative.  If,  however,  it  is  associated  with  a  psychological 
analysis  which  does  not  work  at  all  and  so  points  to  a  more  radical 
correction  than  any  which  Behaviorism  is  in  a  position  to  offer,  it  en- 
counters the  suggestion  that  the  whole  Frage-stellung  it  shares  with 
orthodox  psychology  may  be  mistaken.  It  may  be  necessary  to  trace 
the  source  of  the  trouble  a  long  way  back ;  it  may  be  our  duty  to  point 
out  that  it  may  not  suffice  simply  to  drop  the  antithesis  of  psychical 
and  physical,  which,  however  futile  and  unworkable  it  may  have  be- 
come in  its  present  elaboration,  was  not  originally  a  heaven-descended 
datum  in  the  human  mind,  but  a  difficult  achievement  which  per- 
formed definite  scientific  services.  And  unless  we  can  get  these 
services  performed  in  some  other  way,  it  will  not  relieve  our  philo- 
sophic embarrassment  to  summon  the  behaviorist  simply  to  club 
the  mind  into  unconsciousness.  In  the  end,  however,  I  find  I  can 
pretty  well  accept  Mr.  Russell's  estimate  of  Behaviorism.  I  agree 
that  it  does  not  result  in  an  adequate  account  of  the  data  of  psy- 
chology, though  it  does  excellent  service  in  challenging  the  conven- 
tional descriptions  of  these  data  and  in  paving  the  way  for  their 
systematic  reconsideration. 

I  am  more  inclined  to  deplore  that  Mr.  Russell's  own  method  of 
curing  the  defects  of  our  existing  psychologies  should  turn  out  to  be 
so  atavistic.  It  takes  the  form  of  a  reversion  to  a  type  of  psychol- 
ogizing which  has  had  a  great  past,  but  should  have  no  future. 
One  had  hoped  that  in  spite  of  its  intrinsic  plausibility,  attested 
once  more  by  Mr.  Russell's  conversion  to  it,  it  had  been  definitely 
antiquated.  I  refer  of  course  to  the  psychological  type  of  which 
Hume  is  the  greatest  exponent  and  the  Kantian  Criticism  the  most 
imposing  monument. 

The  characteristic  features  of  this  psychology  are  (1)  as  regards 
its  data,  that  it  is  highly  pluralistic,  (2)  as  regards  its  method,  that 
it  is  abstract  analysis  in  search  of  the  "simple"  and  elemental, 
conducted  from  the  standpoint  of  an  extraneous  observer.  Both 
these  assumptions,  however,  owe  their  undeniable  plausibility,  not 
so  much  to  their  inherent  merit  or  proved  success  in  describing  the 
explicanda,  as  to  the  extraneous  strength  they  derive  from  their 
consonance  with  common-sense  prejudices. 


MR.  RUSSELL'S  PSYCHOLOGY  283 

1.  This  psychological  analysis  assumes  that  it  can  start  with  an  in- 
definite plurality  of  entities  or  facts,  out  of  which  psychic  structures 
can  be  built.     Hume  calls  them  "impressions"  and  "ideas,"  Russell 
"sensations"  and  " images";  but  'both  agree  that  they  are  fundamen- 
tal, elemental,  and  practically  adequate  for  the  construction  of  a  psy- 
chology.    Russell,  for  example,  may  sometimes  be  found  to  declare 
that  his  "main  thesis"  is  that  "all  psychic  phenomena  are  built 
up  out  of  sensations  and  images  alone. ' ' *    Actually  these  structures 
do  require  (and  employ)  a  minimum  of  mortar,  both  in  Hume  and 
in  Russell.     This  is  introduced  under  the  names  of  "association," 
"causality,"  "memory,"  "expectation,"  and  sundry  "relations," 
such  as  "meaning."    But  their  presence  and  activity  are  so  little 
emphasized  that  they  are  even  verbally  denied,  as  in  the  passage  just 
quoted,  and  they  are  supposed  to  have  no  special  significance  for 
psychological  theory.     The  fundamental  feature  primarily  recog- 
nized about  a  mind  is  that  it  is  (or  contains)  a  plurality,  and  that 
its  unity  is  secondary  and  derivative.     Consequently  when  the  prob- 
lem of  its  unity  comes  up,  as  in  the  end  it  must,  this  type  of  psy- 
chology has  need  of  principles  of  synthesis,  to  compact  together 
the  atomic  succession  of  events  into  which  it  has  dissolved  the  mind. 
It  ought,  therefore,  to  be  as  grateful  to  Kantian   apriorism  for 
providing  synthetic  principles  with  such  lavish  prodigality  as  the 
latter  should  be  proud  to  claim  descent  from  the  Humian  '  *  analysis 
of  mind. ' ' 

Not  only,  moreover,  are  the  systems  of  Hume  and  Kant  logically 
interdependent,  but  they  are  also  derived,  psychologically,  from  the 
same  source.  Both  presuppose  the  common-sense  analysis  of  expe- 
rience and  derive  their  real  strength  from  it.  It  is  because  we  all 
habitually  take  our  experience  as  the  product  of  impressions  made 
on  us  by  a  plurality  of  external  things  that  we  find  it  so  easy  to 
accept  Hume's  psychology  as  its  logical  development.  It  is  only  at 
a  much  later  stage  of  psychological  reflection,  when  Hume's  method 
has  clearly  failed  to  account  for  some  of  the  most  patent  facts  of 
ordinary  experience,  that  we  realize  the  need  of  raising  the  problem 
of  psychological  description  ab  initio  and  become  willing  to  inquire 
whether  an  entirely  different  set  of  assumptions  will  not  lead  to  a 
more  adequate  account.  And  then  we  speedily  convince  ourselves 
that  the  plurality,  which  common-sense,  Hume,  and  Russell,  all 
treat  as  a  datum,  is  not  present  in  the  original  experience,  and  is 
at  best  a  construction  resulting  from  a  course  of  philosophic  reflec- 
tion. 

2.  As  regards  method,  Russell's  psychology  possesses  three  char- 
acteristics which  it  is  easy  to  overlook. 

i  Anal  of  Mind,  p.  279.    Cf.  p.  121.    Italics  mine. 


284  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

(a)  That  his  analysis  should  everywhere  seek  for  the  "simple" 
and  the  "element"  is  merely  consequential  on  his  assumption  that 
the  data  are  plural.  He  can,  and  must,  believe  that  there  are  simple 
elements  to  be  discovered,  because  he  has  assumed  that  the  original 
datum  is  a  compositum  and  not  a  continuum. 

(6)  He  can  assume  this,  because  his  method  is  not  concerned 
with  the  actual  course  of  mental  development,  but  with  an  ideal 
description  of  its  products.  It  takes  an  adult  mind  and  rearranges 
its  contents  in  a  systematic  and  esthetically  pleasing  order.  It  does 
not  take  into  account  that  of  such  accounts  there  may  be  a  great 
number,  and  that  neither  their  results  nor  their  procedures  need 
have  any  relevance,  significance  or  value  for  the  study  of  actual 
mental  development. 

For  mental  development  is  not  a  mere  playground  for  theories. 
It  is  an  historically  given  fact  both  in  the  individual  and  in  the  race. 
The  only  questions  that  should  arise  about  it  are  as  to  what  is  the 
most  complete  and  convenient  description  of  what  has  actually 
happened.  There  should,  therefore,  be  only  a  single  history  of  this 
process  that  can  justly  claim  to  be  authentic.  A  psychological  "an- 
alysis" of  mind,  on  the  other  hand,  is  not  thus  strictly  tied  down 
to  a  course  of  happening.  It  can  take  an  actual  mind  and  describe 
its  contents  in  whatever  language  it  prefers.  It  can  choose  the 
standpoint  from  which  it  analyzes,  the  direction  in  which  it  looks, 
the  terminology  it  employs,  the  terminals  it  reaches.  And  all  these 
may  be  varied.  Evidently  therefore  there  may  be  many  psycholog- 
ical analyses  of  mind.  They  may  differ  widely  in  esthetic  merit, 
elegance  and  ease,  and  yet  may  all  fulfill  the  function  of  "analyz- 
ing" mind.  But  there  will  be  no  antecedent  guarantee  that  any  of 
them  will  have  any  affinity  or  relation  to  any  history  of  mental 
development. 

(c)  The  moment  therefore  an  "analysis"  is  required  to  comply 
with  other  than  esthetic  conditions  and  to  conform  to  the  facts  of 
psychic  development,  it  ceases  to  be  a  matter  of  indifference  from 
what  standpoint,  with  what  methods,  and  with  what  purpose,  we 
manipulate  the  mind.  It  will  make  a  great  difference,  e.g.,  whether 
we  conceive  ourselves  as  agents  or  as  spectators,  and  describe  the 
subject-matter  of  our  psychology  as  an  Erlebnis  or  as  an  object 
to  be  contemplated  by  an  extraneous  observer.  The  latter  (if  he 
can  allow  himself  to  forget  that  he  is  observing  with  his  mind)  can 
very  well  come  to  doubt  whether  there  are  minds  to  observe.  For 
the  objects  he  is  observing  are  all  of  them  physical,  i.e.,  bodies  per- 
forming actions  called  "intelligent";  but  he  can  quite  well  ascribe 
their  intelligence  to  habit,  instinct  and  "mnemic  causation,"  with- 
out any  mention  of  consciousness,  desire,  will,  or  purpose. 


MR.  RUSSELL'S  PSYCHOLOGY  285 

This  is  the  method  Mr.  Russell  employs  with  much  ingenuity  and 
success.  He  is  moreover  well  aware  of  what  he  is  doing.  He  re- 
peatedly confesses  that  he  is  "a  trained  observer  with  an  analytic 
attention"  "viewing  man  from  the  outside"  (pp.  298,  255),  who 
admires  the  method  of  behaviorism,  though  he  can  not  quite  admit 
that  "the  analysis  of  knowledge  can  be  effected  entirely  by  means 
of  purely  external  observation"  (pp.  230,  157).  But  even  when  he 
takes  his  stand  within  the  soul,  he  is  still  playing  the  observer.  He 
is  ruthless,  therefore,  towards  "logical  fictions,"  like  the  "subject," 
which  are  not  revealed  by  observation  (p.  141).  He  is  also  aware 
that  his  method  is  anything  but  naive,  that  his  "data"  and  "partic- 
ulars," "sensations,"  "matter,"  "perspectives"  and  "biographies" 
are  anything  but  experiences  of  the  plain  man  and  are  really  highly 
sophisticated  and  elaborated  creations  of  theory  (p.  298). 

What  unfortunately  he  does  not  appear  to  recognize  is  the  exist- 
ence of  alternatives  to  his  procedure,  which  are  at  least  as  capable 
of  apperceiving  the  facts,  of  satisfying  common  sense,  and  even  of 
appreciating  behaviorism.  Mr.  Russell's  blindness  to  these  alterna- 
tives is  so  remarkable  that  I  must  make  an  effort  to  describe  them 
and  to  show  why  and  where  they  may  be  regarded  as  definitely 
superior  to  Russell's  "analysis." 

1.  It  may  be  pointed  out  that  an  external  observer  is  not  well 
placed  to  appreciate  the  biological  significance  of  intelligent  action. 
An  intelligent  act  is  after  all  one  that  is  related  to  the  life,  aims  and 
welfare  of  the  organism  which  performs  it.  It  is  essentially  a  salu- 
tary response  to  the  stimulus  of  a  vital  situation,  in  which  an  un- 
intelligent response  might  be  fatal.  Hence  the  simplest  and  easiest 
form  of  such  response  must  be  adopted  as  our  unit,  if  we  really  mean 
to  trace  the  history  of  mental  development,  and  not  merely  to  amuse 
ourselves  with  fancy  analyses.  This  obvious  consideration  at  once 
non-suits  all  the  "elements"  of  the  ordinary  psychologies.  "Sensa- 
tions," "cognitions,"  "conations,"  and  "feelings,"  are  all  equally 
hard  to  justify  as  occurring  in  fact.  They  not  only  seem  to  be  ex 
post  facto  fictions  of  theory,  but  fictions  that  can  not  possibly  be  con- 
ceived as  original  constituents  of  a  functioning  mind.  For  the 
simple  reason  that  the  simplest  response  accompanied  by  conscious- 
ness implies  the  presence  and  cooperation  of  them  all.  No  actual 
psychic  process  can  conceivably  be  pure  "cognition"  or  mere  "will- 
ing" or  bare  "feeling."  No  mind  that  is  biologically  viable  can 
possibly  be  constructed  out  of  the  "elements"  which  are  postulated 
in  the  traditional  psychologies.  A  biologically  possible  analysis 
can  not  start  from  anything  less  than  the  whole  process  involved  in 
an  act,  viz.,  a  response  to  stimulation  which  is  salutary,  or  harmful, 
and  is  selected  accordingly. 


286  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

On  the  other  hand  there  is  no  reason  why  such  a  response  should 
not  be  treated  as  a  case  of  behavior.  We  may  therefore  concede  to 
behaviorism  that  it  is  a  legitimate  subject  of  inquiry  how  far  be- 
havior is  conscious  and  involves  real  understanding.  There  is  really 
far  more  affinity  between  .behaviorism  and  pragmatism  (as  the  case 
of  Dewey  shows)  than  between  behaviorism  and  Humism.  Only  the 
biologically  minded  pragmatist  will  want  to  know  why,  if  conscious 
activity  exists  and  can  be  detected,  psychological  description  should 
be  bound  to  abstract  from  it.  The  plea  that  the  method  of  natural 
science  abstracts  from  it  and  assumes  the  standpoint  of  the  external 
observer,  is  not  convincing.  For  in  dealing  with  animals  and  atoms 
no  other  standpoint  is  accessible.  But  in  the  case  of  psychology 
we  happen  to  have  direct  access  to  the  inside  of  the  subject.  Being 
agents  ourselves,  we  can  tell  what  agency  feels  like.  Is  it  not  then 
fatuous  to  contend  that  its  nature  can  not  be  known?  Of  course 
the  term  "knowledge"  can  be  technically  restricted  to  what  is 
visible  to  an  external  observer ;  but  to  restrict  psychology  accordingly 
would  merely  .be  to  argue  in  a  circle.  Actually  the  psychologist  has 
a  choice  between  the  two  standpoints ;  he  can  occupy  either,  and  even 
if  he  finds  that  of  the  agent  more  intimate,  fruitful  and  congenial, 
he  can  eke  it  out  with  external  observation  when  this  seems  expedient. 

2.  He  has  a  similar  choice  in  conceiving  his  subject-matter.  He 
is  not  bound  to  postulate  that  a  plurality  of  "sensations"  or  "partic- 
ulars" shall  be  his  datum.  He  may  conceive  his  datum  as  a  con- 
tinuum which  is  gradually  and  progressively  differentiated  into  a 
plurality.  Only,  if  he  does,  he  must  make  the  corresponding  changes 
in  his  formulation  of  psychological  problems.  He  must  no  longer 
represent  the  discovery  of  "simple  elements"  as  the  aim  of  his 
analysis,  but  must  treat  the  mind  as  a  real  entity,  never  less  than  a 
complete  organism  even  in  the  earliest  stages  of  its  growth.  And 
withal  he  should  give  up  the  search  for  "synthetic  principles." 
For,  as  his  mind  never  gets  dissociated  into  atomic  "sensations,"  it 
does  not  need  to  be  put  together  again.  Principles  of  discrimination 
are  what  he  will  need  in  order  to  analyze  his  initial  continuum  into 
a  number  of  distinct  aspects — the  "things"  of  common  sense.  Thus 
what  is  datum  for  one  method  will  be  result  for  the  other,  and  the 
continuity,  which  the  one  labors  vainly  to  attain,  the  other  can  take 
for  granted. 

Upon  trial,  this  alternative  method  develops  several  advantages. 

(a)  It  is  much  easier  to  derive  the  apparent  plurality  in  the 
mind  than  to  construct  its  unity,  and  the  latter  task  has  proved  too 
much  for  the  acutest  philosophers  of  the  last  two  centuries.  If  we 
postulate  a  dust-heap  of  sensations  or  "manifold  of  sense"  as  the 


MB.  RUSSELL'S  PSYCHOLOGY  287 

basis  for  our  reconstruction  of  a  "mind,"  we  set  out  on  a  search 
for  an  elusive  "synthesis."  We  not  only  have  to  put  together  our 
disjointed  jig-saw  puzzle  into  a  coherent  picture,  but  have  to  make 
its  parts  cohere.  And  this  the  synthetic  principles  alleged  can  not 
do.  Alike  whether  they  are  alleged  with  the  skeptical  smile  of  Hume, 
with  the  naive  complacency  of  Kant,  with  the  candid  bewilderment 
of  Mill,  or  with  the  airy  insouciance  of  Russell,  they  inevitably 
provoke  the  question — "But  how  do  your  synthetic  principles  bind 
together  the  dissociated  mind-stuff  you  supply  them  with?"  And 
the  inevitable  answer  is  "Nohow!  "  Hence  Hume,  after  trying 
whether  "associating  ideas  in  the  imagination"  would  not  do2  and 
furtively  smuggling  in  a  "feigned"  self  under  the  name  of 
"memory,"  conceived  as  a  faculty  for  "raising  up  images  of  past 
perceptions"  that  "not  only  discovers  the  identity  but  also  con- 
tributes to  its  production,"3  gaily  confesses  his  bankruptcy.  "If 
perceptions  are  distinct  existences,  they  form  a  whole  only  by  being 
connected  together.  But  no  connections  among  distinct  existences 
are  ever  discoverable."*  So  Hume  despairs  of  explaining  "the 
principles  that  unite  our  successive  perceptions  in  our  thought  or 
consciousness."  Mill,  after  recognizing  associations,  memories  and 
expectations,  is  distressed  to  find  that  they  commit  him  to  the  "in- 
explicable fact"  that  a  mind  "which  ex  hypothesi  is  but  a  series  of 
feelings  can  be  aware  of  itself  as  a  series. ' ' 5  Kant  never  himself  got 
clear  enough  about  the  relations  of  his  epistemology  to  psychology 
to  see  the  difficulty :  but  the  only  sense  in  which  he  can  be  said  to 
have  answered  Hume  is  by  failing,  himself  also,  to  solve  Hume's 
problem.  Of  his  followers  a  few  have  displayed  some  uneasiness 
when  confronted  with  the  awkward  question  how  the  a  priori 
' '  forms ' '  could  make  sure  of  encountering  no  recalcitrance  from  the 
"matter"  of  sensation;  the  majority  realized  that  the  safest  way 
of  dealing  with  an  unanswerable  question  was  not  to  try  to  answer 
it.  So  they  kept  mum  about  it. 

Russell  does  the  next  best  thing ;  he  skips  lightly  over  it  to  start 
with.  The  "subject"  or  "act"  is  "unnecessary  and  fictitious." 
He  can  discover  nothing  "empirically  corresponding  to  the  supposed 
act,"6  and  "theoretically  I  can  not  see  that  it  is  indispensable." 
It  is  the  "ghost"  of  the  subject,  which  in  turn  "once  was  the  full- 
blooded  soul."  Persons  are  just  "bundles,"  and  not  "ingredients 

2  Treatise  (Selby  Bigge),  p.  259. 

s/6.,  p.  260-1. 

«J6.,  p.  635. 

s  Exam,  of  Hamilton,  p.  247. 

•  Analysis  of  Mind,  p.  17. 


288  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

in  the  single  thought."7  No  "observation"  reveals  the  "I,"  which 
is  a  linguistic  convenience,  and  a  logical  fiction.*  After  that,  he 
appeals  to  association,  memory  and  expectation,  like  Hume  and  Mill, 
continues  to  use  the  personal  pronoun  like  every  one  else,  and 
speaks  nonchalantly  of  the  "assent"  and  "attitudes"  involved  in 
belief."  But  he  has  established  no  right  to  any  of  these  things,  and 
has  not  laid  the  ghost  of  the  full-blooded  soul. 

If  on  the  other  hand  we  refuse  to  murder  the  full-blooded  soul 
without  a  trial,  we  need  have  no  trouble  with  the  unity  of  mind. 
We  shall  be  entitled  to  take  it  as  an  organic  whole  (blood  and  all !) 
and  to  consider  merely  how  we  can  cut  it  up  without  hurting  it. 
This  we  shall  do  by  confessing  that  we  were  "analyzing"  it  in 
thought  alone,  admitting  that,  originally  and  as  given,  it  is  a  con- 
tinuum and  the  source  of  all  continuity,  and  by  suggesting  principles, 
not  of  synthesis,  but  of  analysis.  It  will  then  only  remain  to  be 
explained  why  and  how  the  soul  is  taken  as  a  plurality  and  broken 
up  into  "faculties"  and  "elements."  And  this  is  quite  easy. 
When,  as  is  frequently  the  case,  we  are  not  interested  in  all  of  it, 
we  can  neglect  the  whole  and  single  out  "aspects"  or  "parts"  which 
seem  to  us  significant  and  relevant  to  our  momentary  purpose.  But 
it  should  be  clearly  understood  that  this  methodological  dissection 
rests  upon  abstractions  and  fictions.  We  do  not  really  split  up  the 
soul,  and  in  no  wise  detract  from  its  working  unity,  as  any  one  can 
convince  himself  even  in  the  act  of  "contemplating"  his  feelings  or 
his  past.  And  when  we  have  done  contemplating  our  selected  aspect, 
it  is  quite  easy  to  get  rid  of  it  again.  We  have  merely  to  let  it  sink 
back  into  the  continuous  background,  out  of  which  it  was  lifted  and 
from  which  it  was  never  really  separated.  Our  recognition  of  its 
plurality,  therefore,  never  endangers  the  soul's  unity. 

(5)  Neither  need  our  recognition  of  unity  enough  in  the  soui 
to  enable  it  to  function  as  a  mind  prejudice  whatever  plurality  it 
may  be  empirically  expedient  to  recognize.  For  it  does  not  follow 
that  plurality  is  an  illusion,  because  it  is  not  an  original  datum. 
This  only  proves  it  secondary  in  an  epistemological,  not  in  an  onto- 
logical  way.  Plurality  may  yet  be  as  real  and  copious,  as  vital  and 
important,  as  it  is  found  to  be.  No  metaphysical  question  is  pre- 
judged or  prejudiced.  It  is  only  contended  that  plurality  is  not 
given,  but  arrived  at,  and  it  may  be  all  the  better  for  that. 

Moreover,  Mr.  Russell  himself  ought  to  assent  to  this  contention. 
For  he  also  admits  that  by  far  the  greater  part  of  the  plurality  he 

ilb.,  p.  18. 
» 76.,  p.  Ml. 
•  E.g.,  ib.,  pp.  233,  243. 


MR.  RUSSELL'S  PSYCHOLOGY  289 

recognizes  is  not  a  datum  in  the  sense  of  being  initially  given,  but 
is  a  secondary  product  of  scientific  elaboration.  This  comes  out 
well  in  his  account  of  the  ' '  ultimate  brief  existents  that  go  to  make 
up  the  collections  we  call  things  or  persons."10  All  such  "partic- 
ulars," his  "ultimate  simples,"  whether  "the  ultimate  data  of  psy- 
chology" or  "physical  objects,"  are  "constructed  or  inferred."11 
For,  strictly,  data  "do  not  mean  the  things  of  which  we  feel  sure 
before  scientific  study  begins,  but  the  things  which,  when  a  science 
is  well  advanced,  appear  as  affording  grounds  for  other  parts  of 
the  science,"  and  presuppose  "a  trained  observer,  with  an  analytic 
attention,  knowing  the  sort  of  thing  to  look  for  and  sort  of  thing 
that  will  be  important."12  Only  one  little  addition  is  needed  to 
make  this  statement  entirely  acceptable  to  an  activist  psychology  of 
the  sort  I  am  advocating.  Mr.  Russell  should  have  noted  also  that 
a  datum  need  not  be  a  "fact,"  nor  be  expressed  in  a  "proposition 
of  which  the  truth  is  known  without  demonstration, ' ' 13  because  it 
is  enough  that  it  should  be  taken  as  fact,  and  that  its  truth  should 
be  assumed  for  the  purpose  of  the  argument.  For  while  hypothetical 
reasoning  has  just  the  same  formal  features  as  assertoric,  it  is  only 
by  taking  them  hypothetically  that  logical  forms  become  significant 
and  valuable. 

I  welcome  also  Mr.  Russell's  doctrine  of  "perspectives"  and 
"biographies"  so  far  as  it  breaks  up  the  unity  of  the  physical  object. 
This  should  not  only  facilitate  a  recognition  that  the  dichotomy  of 
experience  into  the  psychical  and  the  physical  is  an  artifice,  and  may 
well  be  a  fiction,  but  should  also  moderate  the  blind  and  somewhat 
fanatical  attachment  of  many  realists  to  the  methodological  con- 
structions of  the  sciences.  But  I  think  it  should  be  added  that  the 
composition  of  a  single  object  out  of  a  multitude  of  "perspectives" 
seems  to  be  a  legitimate  process  which  is  pragmatically  justified  in  a 
way  in  which  the  decomposition  of  a  "mind"  is  not.  For  practically, 
i.e.,  as  agents,  we  need  to  recognize  the  plurality  of  things  and  the 
unity  of  souls. 

(c)  It  is  moreover  a  "theoretic"  advantage  also  to  curb  the  mob 
of  "analytical"  fictions  which  have  too  long  been  allowed  to  ruu 
riot  in  psychology.  In  particular,  Mr.  Russell's  accounts  of  "sen- 
sations" and  of  the  cognitive  function  of  "images"  afford  a  welcome 
opportunity  for  the  suppression  of  these  fictions.  For  he  is  well 
aware  of  their  artificial  character  and  of  the  impossibility  of  justify- 

10  Analysis  of  Mind,  p.  193. 
"76.,  p.  300,  105. 
"/ft.,  p.  298. 
is  J6.,  p.  297. 


290  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ing  them  as  data  of  immediate  experience.  He  sees  that  they  are 
constructs  and  can  be  data  only  in  his  "strict"  sense,  though  hardly 
how  futile  their  construction  is.  Thus  he  admits  that  "the  sensation 
is  a  theoretical  core  in  the  actual  experience;  the  actual  experience 
is  the  perception, ' '  "  enriched  by  ' '  mnemic  phenomena. ' '  Defining 
then  "sensation  as  the  non-mnemic  elements  in  a  perception,"  we 
see  that ' '  the  core  of  pure  sensation  is  only  to  be  extracted  by  care- 
ful investigation,"15  and  that  "we  have  to  pare  away  all  that  is 
due  to  habit  or  expectation  or  interpretation." ie  Still  he  sticks  to  it 
that  though  "in  any  other  science  than  psychology  the  datum  is 
primarily  a  perception,  in  which  only  the  sensational  core  is  ulti- 
mately and  theoretically  a  datum"  and  "an  ideal  observer"  has  to 
be  "postulated"  to  "isolate  the  sensation  and  treat  this  alone  as 
datum,"17  yet  "there  certainly  is  a  sensational  core."  18 

I  disagree  on  principle.  Mr.  Russell  has  described  sensation  as 
a  pure  fiction,  though  he  has  made  its  formation  scientifically  intel- 
ligible. The  pure  sensation  is  clearly  not  a  fact  of  immediate  ex- 
perience, and  could  not  conceivably  become  such  a  fact.  For  if  we 
conceived  it  as  occurring  once,  we  should  at  once  have  to  add  that  it 
could  never  occur  again.  On  its  recurrence  it  would  at  once  be 
colored  by  the  results  of  the  first  experience,  even  though  these  were 
not  actually  remembered.  It  is,  therefore,  a  pure  creation  of  psy- 
chological theory. 

And  the  theory  which  generates  it  is  optional  and  unnecessary. 
"We  need  not  even  accept  it  as  a  scientifically  constructed  "datum." 
If  we  seriously  attempt  description  of  actual  experience  and  explore 
the  alternative  possibilities  of  scientific  construction,  we  can  per- 
fectly well  rest  content  with  "perceptions"  as  ultimate  facts  which 
function  as  "elements"  only  in  "biographies."  That  will  mean 
merely  the  adoption  of  an  activist  method  in  psychology,  and  a  tardy 
recognition  of  the  personality  which  it  was  usual  to  abstract  from. 
But  the  reason  for  this  abstraction  was  merely  that  the  other  sciences 
all  appeared  to  make  it,  and  that  the  psychologists  were  anxious  to 
fall  into  line.  But  recent  developments  have  revolutionized  the  situ- 
ation. "Biographies"  are  no  longer  restricted  to  psychology,  and 
"perspectives"  to  art;  science  finds  it  possible,  and  even  necessary, 
to  recognize  them.  The  chemist  has  for  some  purposes  to  take  into 
account  the  history  of  the  stuff  he  handles,  to  consider  whether  it 

«  Anal.,  p.  132. 
"It.,  p.  139. 
«/&.,  p.  140. 
«  n>.,  p.  299. 
"/&.,  p.   140. 


MR.  RUSSELL'S  PSYCHOLOGY  291 

is  thorium-lead  or  uranium-lead  and  in  what  proportions,  and  to 
allow  for  the  "mnemic  phenomena"  it  displays.  The  physicist  must 
locate  the  events,  and  date  the  localities,  of  his  observations,  and  may 
presently  find,  not  merely  that  "man  is  the  measure"  of  everything, 
but  that  no  thing  can  be  measured  except  in  its  own  space  and  at  its 
own  time,  and  ultimately,  perhaps,  by  its  own  leave.18  That  is  the 
meaning  of  Relativity. 

Consequently  it  has  become  timely  to  suggest  that  perceptions  are 
the  real  experiences,  and  are  always  involved  in  a  biography,  which 
it  is  well  to  ascertain;  also  that  psychology  need  not  substitute  any 
fictitious  "data"  for  these  facts.  After  the  deposition  of  "sensa- 
tions" from  their  preeminence,  it  would  no  longer  seem  obligatory 
to  inflate  the  status  of  "images,"  and  to  attribute  to  them  an  im- 
portance which  they  do  not  empirically  appear  to  possess.20 

Thus  the  activist  interpretation  in  psychology  may  justly  appeal 
from  the  sordid  past  of  the  sciences  to  their  dazzling  prospects.  It 
should  not,  however,  neglect  to  fortify  itself  against  some  of  the  more 
obvious  misconceptions.  It  should  not,  e.g.,  plead  guilty  to  the  charge 
of  recalling  from  the  limbo  of  discarded  errors  the  simple  soul-sub- 
stance of  rationalistic  metaphysics.  For  this  may  justly  be  con- 
demned on  the  ground  that  it  involved  a  passivist  conception  of 
substance,  modelled  upon  observation  of  the  external  world,  and 
utterly  alien  to  the  self-maintaining  energy  of  psychic  life.  It  made 
the  soul  into  a  thing,  not  into  a  person.  Divorcing  its  substance 
from  its  "accidents,"  it  could  account  for  none  of  its  empirical 
manifestations,  for  none  of  the  plurality  and  variety  in  its  function- 
ing. The  a  priori  sort  of  unity  it  postulated  was  utterly  useless 
and  incompatible  with  the  "dissociations"  which,  empirically  speak- 
ing, are  more  or  less  normal  in  the  souls  we  actually  know. 

The  activist  theory,  on  the  other  hand,  though  it  repudiates 
atomizing  artifices,  can  make  room  for  any  sort  and  amount  of 
plurality  that  do  not  destroy  all  unity,  and  are  in  fact  required.  It- 
rejects  only  a  pluralism  so  complete  that  psychic  continuity  becomes 
unthinkable.  It  demands  only  that  an  adequate  psychology  should 
face  the  fact  that  some  at  least  of  our  psychic  contents  coagulate 
into  or  inhabit  a  "self"  that  says  "I"  to  them  and  calls  them 
"mine."  Also  that,  to  all  appearance,  they  really  do  belong  to  it. 
This  last  requirement  also  is  essential,  and  is  often  overlooked. 
Transcendentalism,  for  example,  fails  to  solve  the  problem  of  the 
self,  because  its  Ego  is  only  a  universal  function  that  does  not  really 

i»  Mr.  Eussell,  quite  rightly,  points  out  that  not  only  living  things  but  all 
have  biographies  (p.  129). 

20  As  I  have  shown,  against  Mr.  Euasell,  in  Mind,  No.  116,  pp.  693-4. 


292  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

cohere  with  the  psychic  contents  it  "  apperceives. "  Instead  of  being 
any  one  in  particular  the  "I"  it  deduces  might  just  as  well  be  the 
Devil  or  the  Absolute. 

In  conclusion  let  me  say  that  the  questions  I  have  raised  all,  I 
believe,  affect  the  fundamentals  of  Mr.  Russell's  system;  for  in  a 
consistent  philosophy  these  are  the  parts  which  most  demand  atten- 
tion, and  are  most  worth  discussion. 

F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 

CORPUS  CHBISTI  COLLEGE,  OXTORD. 


"IMPLICATION  AND  LINEAR  INFERENCE" 

MIGHT  I  say  a  word  on  one  judgment  and  its  corollary  in  the 
courteous  and  appreciative  review  of  my  book  in  this  JOURNAL 
by  H.  T.  Costello? 

The  point  is  that  he  describes  my  illustration  of  self-evidence 
by  the  proposition  that  two  straight  lines  can  not  enclose  a  space,  as 
"unfortunate."  The  reason  is,  I  gather,  that  experts  do  not  now 
admit  this  proposition  to  be  self-evident.  And  what  I  want  to  main- 
tain is  that  thus  it  becomes  a  far  more  fortunate  illustration  of  my 
argument  than  I  supposed  it  to  be. 

Obviously  it  is  involved  in  my  notion  of  coherence  that  theoreti- 
cally and  in  principle  self-evidence  is  a  matter  of  degree.  There  are 
plenty  of  propositions  no  one  would  trouble  to  interfere  with,  but, 
technically,  there  is  none  which  has  in  itself  absolute  self-evidence. 
I  asserted  this  position  in  my  Logic  and  applied  it  to  the  "Law 
of  Causation,"  and  also  showed  that  the  interpretation  of  the 
"Laws  of  Thought"  was  "relative  and  ambiguous."  Therefore, 
having  later  made  a  concession  for  the  sake  of  argument,  and  under- 
taken to  show  as  a  limiting  case  of  my  theory  a  proposition  which  I 
believed  nearly  every  one  would  feel  as  self-evident,  I  am  fortunate, 
and  not  unfortunate,  when  my  reviewer  batters  down  for  me  the 
wall  I  was  trying  to  breach  and  tells  me  that  the  proposition,  though 
constantly  taken  for  self-evident,  is  not  self-evident  at  all.  That  is 
to  say,  in  the  light  of  a  wider  or  more  precisely  analyzed  whole  of 
experience  than  mine,  its  supposed  necessity  does  not  stand  exam- 
ination. This  is  quite  natural,  and  of  course  is  a  strong  support  to 
my  view,  which  was  originally  formulated  owing  in  part  to  some 
hints  of  Lotze  in  the  same  direction  which  I  thought  were  probably 
out  of  date  today,  and  so  did  not  produce  in  the  discussion  in  my  book. 

I  proceed  to  the  corollary.  The  reviewer's  judgment  that  the 
illustration  is  unfortunate  establishes  to  my  mind  the  point  that  he 


"IMPLICATION  AND  LINEAR  INFERENCE"        293 

does  not  follow  me  in  apprehending  the  test  of  coherence  as  involv- 
ing a  genuinely  •complete  empiricism  and  only  rejecting  one  that  is 
arbitrary  and  partial.  He  does  not  see  how  (as,  e.g.,  Husserl  points 
out)  self -evidence  is  relative  to  the  relevant  whole  of  experience. 
Thus  I  read  in  the  review  (p.  416)  :  ''Looking  upon  the  process  as 
an  internal  dialectic  of  coherence  within  thought,  they  slur  over  the 
empirical  checks  which  actually  knock  a  thought-process  into  shape 
by  unexpected  blows  from  without  itself."  So  (p.  417)  :  "Only 
empiricism  can  select  the  true  one. ' ' 

Mr.  Russell  is  in  the  same  mythical  tradition  (Analysis  of  Mind, 
p.  268,  treating  expressly  of  the  coherence  method) .  ' '  The  attempt  to 
deduce  the  world  iby  pure  thought  is  attractive. — But  nowadays 
most  men  admit  that  beliefs  must  be  tested  by  observation,  and  not 
merely  by  the  fact  that  they  harmonize  with  other  beliefs.  A  con- 
sistent fairy-tale,"  etc. 

And  Mr.  Arnauld  Reid  in  the  Philosophical  Review,  January, 
1922,  treats  perception  as  a  test  other  than  and  external  to  "coher- 
ence." 

They  must  all,  surely,  be  speaking  of  something  much  less  simple 
on  one  side,  and  much  less  fundamental  on  the  other,  than  what  I  am 
talking  about.  As  early  as  in  the  concluding  chapters  of  Knowledge 
and  Reality  (1885)  I  pointed  out  in  detailed  analysis  the  obvious 
fact  that  every  precise  perception  and  every  scientific  observation 
is  in  itself  a  crucial  experiment  demonstrating  that  inference  is  by 
coherence.  There  is,  therefore,  no  alternative  method.  The  human 
mind  in  the  pursuit  of  truth  works  in  no  other  Way.  The  simplest 
and  most  classical  analysis  of  the  facts,  apart  from  the  many  well- 
known  passages  of  Mr.  Bradley  and  others,  is,  I  should  say,  in  Nettle- 
ship 's  Logic  Lectures  (Remains,  Vol.  I,  pp.  181  ff.). 

We  always  test  a  sense-perception  as  Macbeth  tested  his  vision  of 
the  dagger,  by  trying  if  it  brings  with  it  something  else  we  expect 
it  to  bring.  The  mind  is  potentially  a  system,  and  puts  its  ques- 
tions, or  demands  its  answers,  in  systematic  form. 

This  characteristic  procedure  has  nothing  directly  to  do  with  any 
further  question  about  the  ultimate  incompleteness  of  truth.  It 
has  nothing  whatever  to  do  with  ideas  of  an  internal  dialectic,  of 
coherence  within  thought,  or  with  deductions  by  pure  thought,  or 
with  consistent  fairy-tales,  or  with  a  contrast  between  thought  and 
empirical  checks  or  perception  or  observation.  Does  no  realist  to- 
day think  it  worth  while  to  consider  what  goes  on  in  any  careful 
perception  or  observation  or  on  what  its  precision  and  truth  value 
depend  ?  It  is  really  as  if  the  hoary  jest  of  our  childhood  about  the 
German  who  evolved  the  camel  out  of  his  moral  consciousness  were 


294  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

hanging  about  the  minds  of  realists,  and  prevented  them  from  attend- 
ing to  what  students  of  actual  working  logic  are  talking  about.  I 
am  much  inclined  to  think  that  some  obsolete  superstition  of  the 
kind  is  actually  at  work. 

BERNARD  BOSANQUET. 
OXSHOTT,  ENGLAND. 


THE  VERIFICATION  OF  STANDARDS  OF  VALUE 

IT  is  a  familiar  contention  of  pragmatism  that  the  truth  as  well 
as  the  value  of  ideas  is  to  be  judged  by  their  consequences  in 
action.  This  theory  has  been  applied  by  Professor  Dewey  to  the 
subject  of  practical  judgments  and  moral  standards.  "The  truth  of 
practical  judgments,"  he  writes,  "  ...  is  constituted  by  the  issue. 
The  determination  of  end-means  (constituting  the  terms  and  rela- 
tions of  the  practical  proposition)  is  hypothetical  until  the  course 
of  action  indicated  has  been  tried.  The  event  or  issue  of  such  action 
is  the  truth  or  falsity  of  the  judgment." 1 

In  conduct  "principles,  criteria,  laws  are  intellectual  instruments 
for  analyzing  individual  or  unique  situations. ' ' 2 
Generalized  and  classified  goods  are  tools  of  insight,  and  in  ethics 
"validation,  demonstration,  become  experimental,  a  matter  of  con- 
sequences. ' '  * 

Up  to  the  present  the  advocates  of  this  theory  have  been  mainly 
occupied  with  defending  its  central  thesis  against  the  formalism  of 
older  ethical  methods.  They  have  accordingly  made  little  if  any 
attempt  to  apply  it  in  testing  specific  current  ideals  and  standards 
of  value.  They  have  rather  been  disposed  to  avoid  such  an  attempt, 
on  the  ground  that  it  would  involve  the  very  failing  of  ethics  which 
they  attack,  a  tendency  to  excessive  and  arbitrary  generalization. 
Art  and  practical  conduct,  therefore,  rather  than  science,  have 
seemed  to  them  the  proper  fields  for  developing  and  testing  stand- 
ards.4 

Such  procedure,  however,  is  subject  to  the  obvious  limitations, 
recognized  by  pragmatists,  of  all  common  sense  thinking  in  com- 
parison with  scientific.5 

The  latter  must  no  doubt  abandon  its  claim  to  provide  absolute 

i  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  p.  346. 
»  Reconstruction  in  Philosophy,  p.  162. 
*n>id.,  pp.  169,  174. 

*Cf.  John  Dewey,  The  Influence  of  Darwin  on  Philosophy,  p.  71;  Essays 
in  Experimental  Logic,  pp.  374-381. 
«  Dewey,  How  We  Think,  ch.  XI. 


THE  VERIFICATION  OF  STANDARDS  OF  VALUE  295 

rules  for  conduct.  Yet,  granting  this,  the  possibility  remains  that 
some  of  the  conceptions  for  which  it  has  claimed  too  much  author- 
ity may  contain  as  hypotheses  a  measure  of  truth  and  value  under 
certain  conditions;  that  the  power  and  scope  of  experimental  sci- 
ence, furthermore,  may  be  utilized  in  developing  and  testing  such 
hypotheses,  on  a  basis  of  past  experience  and  subject  to  the  ultimate 
verdict  of  future  events.  Are  there  ways  in  which  science  can  be 
so  used  without  unwarranted  generalizing? 


It  has  been  noted  that  pragmatic  verification  and  valuation  con- 
sist at  least  partially  in  discovering  and  comparing  consequences. 
Any  prediction  of  future  results  must  be  made  largely  on  a  basis  of 
past  experience  or  history.  To  this  extent,  then,  the  verification  and 
valuation  of  standards  are  studies  in  the  history  of  ideas,  and  are 
subject  to  no  more  dangers  than  attend  all  such  historical  narrative. 
In  observing  the  past  and  present  operation  of  specific  standards, 
ethical  research  has  thus  a  clear  field  before  it. 

Disagreement  on  the  general  nature,  basis  and  authority  of  moral 
ideas  is  no  obstacle  to  such  research.  It  is  clear,  at  least,  that  many 
ideas  such  as  freedom,  justice,  happiness,  growth  and  control  are 
current  in  human  thinking,  and  are  often  described  as  ends,  ideals 
and  standards,  though  conceived  and  used  in  different  ways.  Some 
denote  abstract  qualities  in  a  catalogue  of  virtues,  others  the  con- 
crete objects  of  desire  or  contemplation;  some  are  products  of  un- 
reflective  instinct  and  custom,  others  of  moral  theory;  some  are 
treated  as  absolute  rules,  others  as  objects  of  worship  or  hypotheses 
in  experiment;  some  are  individual,  trivial  and  ephemeral,  others 
racial,  enduring,  wide  in  application  and  in  influence.  But  what- 
ever their  form  and  function,  if  they  operate  in  human  thought 
and  conduct  at  all,  science  may  attempt  to  describe  their  operation. 

Such  an  attempt  would  imply  for  the  procedure  of  ethical  in- 
quiry the  examination  of  specific  concepts,  especially  those  of  major 
scope  and  influence,  rather  than  a  study  of  value  and  value-stand- 
ards in  general;  the  treatment  of  these  concepts  as  factors  in  conduct 
rather  than  as  static  theories,  with  emphasis  rather  on  their  applica- 
tion than  on  their  formulation  and  justification ;  the  observation  of 
actual  problems  and  decisions,  with  analysis  of  the  part  which  stand- 
ards have  played  therein.  "What  functions,"  the  observer  would 
inquire,  "has  this  concept  been  intended  to  fulfil,  and  why?  How 
has  it  carried  out  these  functions,  and  what  other  consequences  have 
followed?  "  The  appropriate  sources  for  such  study  are  less  in 
systems  of  ethics  than  in  history,  literature  and  applied  science,  where 


296  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

standards  are  described,  developed  and  followed  in  contact  with 
events. 

The  difficulties  in  such  an  inquiry  are  obvious.  To  trace  the 
history  of  any  scientific  concept  is  to  deal,  especially  if  the  concept 
is  old  and  much  used,  with  a  rather  nebulous  subject-matter.  It 
begins,  as  a  rule,  at  no  assignable  date,  it  has  no  continuous  growth, 
as  from  seed  to  flowering,  it  has  at  no  stage  a  clearly  outlined  iden- 
tity, and  it  appears  to  the  observer  less  as  a  unified  intellectual  in- 
strument than  as  a  place  of  entrance  to  a  world  of  tangled  theories. 
One  contemplating  such  a  history  may  readily  feel  the  illusion  of 
watching  a  shifting  mist  of  words,  without  structure  or  sequence,  and 
forget  that  each  period  may  have  been  a  serious  attempt  at  describ- 
ing stable  facts  or  formulating  persistent  desires.  Each  participant 
in  the  history  has  probably  felt  the  impulse,  more  or  less  conscious, 
to  sharpen  the  outlines  of  his  terms  by  cutting  off  unwanted  accre- 
tions of  meaning,  then  by  adding  his  own  commentary  to  set  up  a 
more  lasting  and  unequivocal  system  of  relations  between  names, 
ideas  and  reality.  But  the  new  definitions  often  prove  scarcely 
less  transitory  than  the  theories  of  fact.  Ideas  are  shifted  from 
name  to  name,  and  rival  theories  marshal  them  in  conflicting  orders, 
until  particular  concepts  lose  all  recognizable  substance. 

A  single  concept,  as  a  recurrent  theme  in  intellectual  history,  is 
accordingly  no  easy  object  to  follow.  At  any  given  time  it  has 
probably  some  recognized  name,  such  as  "democracy,"  and  the 
career  of  this  name  may  .be  followed  from  its  etymological  origin  or 
its  equivalents  in  earlier  tongues,  through  successive  gains  and  losses 
of  connotation,  through  various  roles  in  theory  and  up  to  its  status 
in  modern  discourse.  But  this  inquiry,  though  of  use  for  some 
purposes,  would  fall  short  of  the  information  required  as  data  for 
verification — a  story  of  the  operation  of  the  concept.  For  a  stand- 
ard, like  any  other  idea,  is  more  than  a  name,  symbol  or  concrete 
embodiment.  It  is  a  complex  of  meanings,  which  the  symbol  binds 
together  and  points  out,  and  the  effect  of  such  a  symbol  upon  thought 
may  include  the  influence  of  all  these  current  meanings.  Since 
they,  rather  than  the  name,  constitute  the  standard,  a  history  of  the 
standard 's  operation  must  include  their  history,  whether  or  not  they 
have  always  borne  the  present  name.  A  concept  may  be  newly  put 
together,  but  if  it  consists  of  older  ideas,  its  history  is  a  continuation 
of  theirs.  To  attempt  a  disentangling  of  such  threads,  and  an  ac- 
count of  their  intermingling  with  the  rest  of  experience — other  ideas, 
desires,  emotions,  the  forces  of  environment — may  well  be  a  slow  and 
dubious  task. 

Yet  these  difficulties  are  not  altogether  insuperable.  The  study 
of  the  history  and  influence  of  ideas,  far  from  being  considered  im- 


THE  VERIFICATION  OF  STANDARDS  OF  VALUE  297 

possible,  forms  a  steadily  increasing  part  of  all  historical  writing. 
Though,  confused  at  times,  ideas  can  achieve  a  degree  of  integrity, 
especially  when  as  social  ideals  or  scientific  concepts  they  are  per- 
sistently redefined.  Some  have  been,  furthermore,  evolved  through 
a  fairly  continuous  development,  or  constructed  out  of  elements 
whose  antecedents  are  likewise  recognizable.  To  describe  the  main 
outlines  of  the  history  of  such  ideas  may  prove  to  be  in  some  measure 
possible. 

In  addition  to  study  of  past  experience,  the  choice  of  hypotheses 
in  conduct  involves  an  interest  in  the  future:  not  alone  "how  has 
this  standard  acted?  "  but  "how  may  it  be  expected  to  act  in  other 
situations?  "  To  whatever  extent  situations  are  unique,  novel  and 
surprising,  future  effects  can  not  be  clearly  foreseen.  But  so  far 
as  past  experience  can  be  utilized,  similarities  detected  and  combina- 
tions of  events  foreseen,  decision  can  be,  and  is  in  practise  assisted 
by  imagination — the  construction  of  hypothetical  situations  and  re- 
sponses in  advance  of  action.  Can  ethics  thus  estimate  the  probable 
consequences  of  standards  under  conditions  not  to  be  found  in 
past  experience  ? 

Some  attempt  at  such  hypothetical  reasoning  is  made  in  almost 
every  scientific  argument  that  attacks  or  defends  a  proposed  policy, 
as  in  theories  of  government  or  economics.  Its  uncertainty  in  pre- 
diction is  obvious,  and  it  runs  the  constant  risk,  through  the  need 
of  imagining  conditions  in  a  more  simple  and  general  form  than 
they  occur,  of  overlooking  important  contingencies.  Yet  it  is  a 
necessary  part  of  any  reflection  that  aims  not  at  mere  understanding 
of  the  past,  but  at  appraisal  and  adoption  of  purposes.  Such  con- 
sideration by  ethics  of  the  major  policies  with  which  it  deals  is  thus  a 
logical  extension  of  the  procedure  necessary  in  all  applied  science. 
If  ethics  is  to  achieve  conclusions  that  are  applicable  in  practise, 
it  must  attempt  to  forecast  the  probable  consequences  of  following 
certain  standards,  in  relation  to  certain  typical  conditions.  In  what 
kinds  of  situation,  in  other  words,  might  a  given  standard  be  applied  1 
What  would  be  its  probable  effect,  if  certain  other  factors  were 
present?  What  emotional,  instinctive  or  habitual  responses  would 
it  tend  to  stimulate  ?  What  rational  inferences  would  it  imply,  and 
what  alternatives  in  action  would  it  tend  to  select  and  favor  ?  What 
later  consequences  might  then  be  expected  ? 

The  decisive  step  in  verification  still  remains  to  be  taken,  even 
after  past  and  probable  future  consequences  are  known.  Conse- 
quences themselves  may  be  subject  to  varying  appraisal.  Beyond 
certain  limits,  it  can  not  be  expected  that  this  final  step  should  be 
made.  The  pragmatic  notion  of  truth  implies  abandonment  of  the 


298  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

attempt  at  absolute  verdicts,  whether  on  a  basis  of  consequences  or 
not.  Such  verdicts  would  themselves  require  standards,  and  these 
latter  also  would  be  subject  to  dispute.  No  appraisal  may  be  ex- 
pected to  result  from  the  above  research,  then,  except  of  a  tentative 
and  approximate  nature,  expressed  in  terms  of  comparison,  and  with 
reference  to  specific  conditions. 

A  knowledge  of  the  consequences  of  a  standard  does,  however,  pro- 
vide data  for  appraising  it  by  whatever  other  standards  are  accepted. 
In  speaking  of  the  truth  of  ideas,  for  example,  Professor  Dewey 
proposes  as  a  test  "that  satisfaction  which  arises  when  the  idea  as 
working  hypothesis  or  tentative  method  is  applied  to  prior  existences 
in  such  a  way  as  to  fulfil  what  it  intends."  •  William  James's  "real 
doctrine  is  that  a  belief  is  true  when  it  satisfies  both  personal  needs 
and  the  requirements  of  objective  things.  Speaking  of  pragmatism, 
he  says,  'Her  only  test  of  probable  truth  is  what  works  best  in  the 
way  of  leading  us,  what  fits  every  part  of  life  best  and  combines  wtih 
the  collectivity  of  experience's  demands,  nothing  being  omitted.'  "T 
"Truth  as  utility  means  service  in  making  just  that  contribution  to 
reorganization  in  experience  that  the  idea  or  theory  claims  to  be 
able  to  make."8 

According  to  this  test,  then,  a  comparison  between  the  intended 
and  the  accomplished  or  probable  consequences  would  be  tentative 
verification.  More  specifically,  the  standard  in  question  may  be 
found  to  rest  upon  self-contradictory  arguments,  or  on  an  unverified 
belief  regarding  the  effects  of  certain  actions.  It  may  be  found  to 
produce  failure,  discord  and  pain.  Such  conclusions  may  fall  short, 
philosophically,  of  absolute  verdicts  on  truth  and  value,  but  in  in- 
telligent conduct  they  have  all  the  cogency  of  such  verdicts,  and 
more  concrete  meaning. 

To  know  and  compare  the  working  of  current  standards,  in  other 
words,  is  to  know  their  interrelation ;  to  know  which  cooperate  and 
confirm  each  other,  which  deny  and  conflict ;  to  find  areas  of  agree- 
ment and  areas  of  dispute  or  ignorance.  In  practise  this  is  equiva- 
lent to  a  recognition  of  certain  main  lines  of  conduct  which  are, 
though  not  certainly  good,  less  questioned  than  others,  and  which 
illuminate  by  contrast  the  fields  where  discovery  and  innovation 
are  more  needed. 

The  choice  of  hypotheses  in  conduct  is  of  course  not  confined 
to  selection  between  ideals  already  formulated,  or  even  to  continuous 

•  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  p.  320. 

•  Ibid.,  p.  324,  quoting  James 'a  Pragmatism,  p.  80;  cf.  also  The  Influence 
of  Darwin  on  Philotophy,  pp.  95,  150. 

•  .Reconstruction  in  Philosophy,  p.  157. 
and 


THE  VERIFICATION  OF  STANDARDS  OF  VALUE  299 

development  of  them.  Future  experience  may  suggest  conceptions 
which  require  to  be  expressed  in  entirely  new  terms,  and  to  be  re- 
garded as  distinct  from  the  old.  The  science  of  ethics  can  doubtless 
aid  in  the  process  of  discovering  and  interpreting  the  data  for  such 
hypotheses.  But  several  considerations  warrant  present  emphasis  on 
the  study  of  older  concepts.  They  contain  an  accumulation  of  long 
experience  with  the  chief  activities  of  life,  whose  testimony  has  not 
yet  been  agreed  upon.  Future  experience  can  hardly  be  quite  dis- 
continuous with  the  past,  or  produce  ideals  unaffected  by  it.  The 
formulation  of  new  standards  can  not  confidently  be  attempted  with- 
out some  decision  upon  the  validity  of  the  old,  and  the  problem  of 
testing  them  when  formed  is  not  unlike  that  of  judging  older  and 
more  familiar  subject-matter.  Although  the  present  situation  in 
ethics,  however,  may  suggest  the  need  of  attention  to  historic  ideals, 
new  and  proposed  conceptions  as  well  may  be  examined  with  a  view 
to  discovering  their  actual  and  possible  consequences  in  relation  to 
other  factors  in  experience. 

Pragmatism  and  the  empirical  theories  which  preceded  it  have 
amply  demonstrated  the  futility  of  rigid  and  premature  moral 
generalizations.  But  a  consistent  ethical  pluralism  will  not  be  con- 
tent with  wholesale  rejection  or  neglect  of  all  general  standards.  It 
will  examine  them  separately  and  in  comparison  as  possible  instru- 
ments in  conduct,  to  discover  if  some  are  perhaps  more  true  in 
assertion  and  more  useful  in  function  than  others.  If  the  funded 
experience  of  the  past  concerning  good  and  bad  is  to  be  made  avail- 
able for  use  in  present  action,  the  work  of  organizing  it  must  be 
carried  on  by  the  sciences,  such  as  ethics,  which  concern  themselves 
with  problems  of  value.  And  if  these  sciences  are  to  accomplish 
more  than  destructive  criticism  and  inconclusive  description  of 
social  and  psychological  processes,  they  must  undertake  the  syste- 
matic development  and  appraisal  of  hypothetical  standards  of  value. 


The  following  questions  are  possible  specific  modes  of  inquiry 
into  the  operation  of  a  standard: 

What  are  its  general  meanings  as  at  present  accepted,  its  defini- 
tions, descriptions,  constituent  ideas,  implied  assertions?  Are  they 
at  present  widely  different,  so  as  to  make  the  standard  ambiguous, 
and  act  in  different  ways  ? 

What  are  their  histories?  How  have  they  come  together  to  form 
a  more  or  less  coherent  conception?  What  associations  have  they 
had  with  other  theories,  problems,  events  and  conditions  ? 

For  what  functions  has  the  standard   (or  its  several  elements, 


300  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

if  they  have  operated  independently)  been  used  or  intended?  Ag 
descriptive  law  or  concept?  As  object  of  desire,  admiration,  con- 
templation, idealization,  reverence,  worship?  As  aim  or  policy? 
Immediate,  ulterior,  ultimate,  summwm  bonumf  As  standard,  crite- 
rion, guide  in  decision  and  valuation?  Subordinate  to  others,  or 
supreme?  Absolute  or  hypothetical?  What  beliefs  and  aims  are 
implied  by  so  using  the  concept? 

By  whom  has  it  been  used  ?  What  sorts  of  people  have  rejected 
or  abandoned  it?  When  has  this  acceptance  or  rejection  occurred? 
Under  what  circumstances?  In  what  sorts  of  problem? 

What  factors  have  led  to  this  acceptance  or  rejection?  What 
instincts,  habits,  customs,  preferences?  Are  these  usual  or  excep- 
tional? What  environmental  conditions  have  been  influential? 
What  beliefs,  premises,  evidence,  inferences,  have  led  to  acceptance 
or  rejection,  especially  in  regard  to  the  nature  of  the  universe,  of 
man  and  his  place  in  it,  and  in  regard  to  the  probable  consequences 
of  certain  ways  of  acting?  Can  these  be  judged  as  true  or  false? 

What  immediate  consequences  tend  to  follow  its  use?  As  actu- 
ally applied?  If  consistently  and  thoroughly  applied?  If  there  is 
a  difference  what  has  led  to  it?  What  responses  in  emotion  or 
action  does  it  stimulate?  What  judgments  and  inferences  does  it 
entail  ?  What  effect  has  it  in  selecting  between  alternatives,  in  reach- 
ing decisions,  choices,  solutions?  Does  it  indicate  the  selection  of 
certain  types  of  alternatives  rather  than  others?  Entirely,  or  on 
a  basis  of  comparative  amounts  or  degrees?  What  ones,  and  by 
what  specifications?  Does  it  select  in  use  as  it  is  expected  to;  i.e., 
does  it  fulfil  its  intended  function?  Are  its  meanings  and  sugges- 
tions different  in  practise  from  its  formal  definitions?  What  other 
factors,  organic,  intellectual,  environmental,  cooperate  to  produce 
these  results? 

Are  the  situations  in  which  it  can  be  applied  frequent,  important, 
crucial,  confined  to  particular  times  and  places  or  lasting  and  wide- 
spread ?  For  what  types  of  alternative  does  it  indicate  no  selection  ? 
What  changes  have  taken  place  in  its  mode  of  functioning? 

With  what  other  standards  does  it  interact,  theoretically  or  prac- 
tically? With  what  ones  would  it  interact  if  consistently  applied 
whenever  possible?  Does  it  tend  to  conflict  with  these?  To  what 
extent  ?  With  any  margin  of  agreement  ?  What  has  produced  this 
conflict?  Does  the  standard  corroborate,  agree  with  others?  To 
what  extent?  As  means,  end,  or  in  coordinate  status?  In  what 
types  of  problem  does  it  interact  with  others,  and  with  what  results? 
What  are  its  relations  to  scientific  knowledge  other  than  value- 
standards? 


BOOK  REVIEWS  301 

What  later  consequences,  organic,  emotional,  intellectual,  individ- 
ual, social,  tend  to  follow  its  use?  Which  are  constant  and  which 
confined  to  particular  times  and  places  ?  What  other  factors  combine 
to  produce  them?  Which  are  expected  by  the  persons  who  use 
the  standards,  and  which  are  unexpected  ?  What  would  follow  if  the 
standard  were  more  consistently  carried  out?  To  what  extent  do 
these  results  (actual  and  possible)  agree  with,  conflict  with  or  re- 
direct the  more  constant  impulses,  desires  and  capacities  of  human, 
nature  ? 

In  what  ways  may  the  standard  and  its  consequences  be  modified  ? 

THOMAS  MUNRO. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Manhood  of  Humanity;  The  Science  and  Art  of  Human  Engineer- 
ing. ALFRED  KORZYBSKI.  New  York:  E.  P.  Button  &  Com- 
pany. 1921.  Pp.  xiii-f-264. 

In  the  preface  the  author  announces  that  (p.  ix)  "This  book 
is  primarily  a  study  of  Man  and  ultimately  embraces  all  the  great 
qualities  and  problems  of  Man." 

Count  Alfred  Korzybski  temperamentally  seems  to  be  a  phi- 
losopher and  poet  who  was  trained  to  be  a  mathematician,  engineer 
and  soldier.  His  natural  inclinations  have  led  him  to  be  intensely 
interested  in  humanity.  In  trying  to  explain  human  behavior  he 
has  used  mathematical  and  engineering  terms  and  figures  of  speech. 
The  sub-title  of  this  volume  "The  Science  and  Art  of  Human 
Engineering"  means  the  directing  of  the  energies  and  capacities 
of  human  beings  to  the  advancement  of  human  weal. 

Man  has  brought  much  suffering  upon  himself  because  he  has 
been  ignorant  concerning  himself,  so  in  order  to  get  a  better  under- 
standing of  humanity  the  author  has  proposed  a  mathematical  in- 
vestigation of  the  problem.  He  claims  that  mathematics  must  be- 
come the  basis  of  the  social  sciences  because  of  its  characteristic 
precision,  sharpness  and  completeness  of  definitions.  The  natural 
sciences  have  gone  on  much  faster  than  the  "so-called  social  sci- 
ences" because  they  have  used  mathematical  methods.  Humanity 
is  said  to  be  in  its  infancy  because  of  so  much  purposeless  sacrifice 
and  wasted  energy. 

A  very  novel  explanation  of  the  relation  of  mankind  to  other 
organic  life  is  offered.  Plants  as  living  organisms  appropriate  the 
basic  energies  of  the  sun,  soil  and  air.  They  constitute  the  lowest 
order  of  life.  This  life  order  or  capacity  is  represented  by  the 


302  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

first  dimension  or  by  dimension  I.  This  peculiar  quality  is  called 
"basic-energy-binding"  or  4 '  chemistry  -binding. " 

Animals  possess  the  autonomous  power  to  move  about  in  space. 
This  power  places  them  in  a  higher  order.  They  have  "chemistry- 
binding"  power  but  their  peculiar  power  lies  in  conquering  space. 
Animals  have,  therefore,  a  two-dimensional  life  or  are  living  in  life 
dimension  II  characterized  as  "space-binding." 

Man,  like  the  animals,  has  chemistry-  and  space-" binding" 
power,  but  in  addition  to  this  he  has  the  power  to  profit  by  experi- 
ence— the  experience  of  past  generations.  Every  succeeding  gen- 
eration builds  upon  the  accumulated  knowledge  of  the  past,  while 
the  animal  begins  its  life  history  at  the  same  point  as  preceding 
generations.  This  quality  or  power  Korzybski  has  called  "time- 
building."  In  life  it  represents  dimension  III.  Such  then  is  the 
proposed  conception  of  man — one  whose  glory  consists  in  his  pecu- 
liar capacity  for  binding  time.  The  power  to  "bind  time"  is  a 
perfectly  natural  power  and  the  power  to  act  in  a  time-binding 
capacity  becomes  the  measure  of  human  progress.  Time-binding 
is  the  energy  that  civilizes,  it  produces  wealth,  it  is  the  great  crea- 
tive power.  Humans  have  the  power  to  continue  where  the  past 
generation  stopped,  profiting  by  all  previous  generations.  The 
beaver  builds  his  dams  the  same  without  gaining  anything  from  past 
generations.  The  progress  of  man  then  should  become  faster  from 
generation  to  generation.  The  natural  law  of  this  increment  can 
be  shown  to  follow  the  law  of  logarithmic  increase  (pp.  90-92). 
Thus,  if  P  is  the  progress  made  in  a  given  generation,  and  if  R  is 
the  ratio,  then  the  progress  made  in  the  second  generation  is  PR, 
and  that  of  the  third  is  PR2  and  that  made  in  a  single  Tth  genera- 
tion will  be  PRT~l.  The  expression  PR7"-1  is  called  an  exponential 
function  of  time.  The  immortal  offspring  of  the  ' '  marriage  of  Time 
and  human  Toil"  increase  in  a  marvelous  manner,  especially  when 
we  consider  the  vast  number  of  generations  that  have  already  con- 
tributed or  should  have  contributed  to  our  welfare. 

Here  we  see  the  need  of  a  tecbnologized  social  science.  Human 
progress  will  go  on  at  a  rate  measured  by  a  rapidly  increasing  ge- 
ometric progression  if  we  acquire  sense  enough  to  let  it  do  so. 

Wealth,  according  to  this  teacher,  consists  of  the  fruit  of  man's 
time-binding  capacity — "the  living  work  of  the  dead." 

The  closing  chapters  of  the  book  emphasize  the  importance  of 
the  time-binding  activities  with  a  view  toward  the  happiness  of  all 
humanity.  He  finally  proposes  a  Department  of  Coordination  or 
Cooperation  which  is  to  be  the  nucleus  of  a  civilization  developed 
along  mathematical-engineering  lines.  This  development  would 
bring  about  the  greatest  true  liberty  and  happiness. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  303 

Three  appendices  are  included  in  the  volume  with  the  following 
titles:  (1)  Mathematics  and  Time-Binding,  (2)  Biology  and  Time- 
Binding,  (3)  Engineering  and  Time-Binding. 

It  is  evident  that  the  whole  discussion  rests  on  the  so-called 
"time-binding"  capacity  or  power  of  the  human  being.  Evidently 
what  is  meant  by  time-binding  is  the  capacity  to  profit  by  experi- 
ence as  the  result  of  associative  memory  or  what  has  come  to  be 
known  as  intelligence.  Although  the  author  probably  would  not 
approve  of  this  statement,  yet  it  is  evident  that  mathematical  fig- 
ures of  speech  have  been  employed  to  describe  facts  that  have  been 
considered  in  every  important  study  of  human  behavior. 

Before  the  ratio  of  progress  can  be  worked  out,  or  before  a 
formula  for  normal  human  development  can  be  written,  it  will  be 
necessary  to  have  standards  of  measurement  to  see  if  the  relations 
are  as  they  have  been  assumed.  Psychology  (classified  on  page  25 
with  philosophy,  law  and  ethics  as  "private  theories"  or  "verbal- 
isms") as  the  science  of  human  behavior  has  already  done  much  in 
measuring  intelligence  with  its  intelligence-quotient  and  other 
psychometric  methods.  The  study  of  human  behavior  by  those 
who  have  been  especially  trained  has  shown  that  an  a  priori  assump- 
tion of  mathematical  formulae  is  a  false  procedure. 

A  few,  but  their  tribe  decreaseth,  of  the  social  investigators 
still  look  upon  man  as  supernatural,  but  most  of  those  in  good 
standing  study  humanity  from  an  empirical  point  of  view  and 
organize  their  data  quantitatively  wherever  standards  of  measure- 
ment are  available. 

The  enthusiasm  of  the  author  has  led  him  to  suggest  that  mathe- 
matics per  se  can  solve  the  problem  of  humanity.  What  is  needed 
is  the  help  or  service  of  mathematics  in  solving  problems  that  are 
already  clearly  defined  in  the  minds  of  real  social  scientists. 

The  Manhood  of  Humanity  contributes  very  little  to  the  social 
sciences,  except  some  interesting  mathematical  and  engineering 
analogies.  The  plea  for  exact  and  scientific  methods  in  the  study 
of  humanity  and  the  warning  against  mystical  or  prejudicial  at- 
titudes is  to  be  commended. 

Humanity  is  still  before  us,  with  us  and  in  us,  with  its  re- 
sponses to  complex  and  remote  stimuli,  and  with  its  complicated, 
delayed  responses.  Humanity  still  challenges  first  the  biologist, 
then  the  psychologist,  and  finally  the  sociologist  for  an  explana- 
tion. The  Science  of  Humanity  will  be  the  synthesis  of  all  sciences 
and  not  the  outgrowth  of  mathematics  merely. 

J.  V.  BREITWTESER. 
UNIVERSITY  OP  CALIFORNIA. 


304  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Die  Deutsch  Philosophic  der  Oegenwart  in  Selbstdarstellungen, 
RAYMUND  SCHMIDT,  editor.  Leipzig:  Felix  Meiner,  1921.  Vol- 
umes 1  and  2,  Pp.  228;  203. 

Conceive  of  a  history  of  European  philosophy  in  which  each  of 
the  authors  had  presented  his  own  views  in  final  and  well  considered 
form.  It  would  be  a  fascinating  book  to  read.  Less  enviable,  per- 
haps, would  be  the  task  of  the  editor.  If  he  had  a  conscientious 
desire  to  make  his  volume  uniform  in  any  sense,  he  might  find  dif- 
ficulty. Not  only  would  there  be  a  tendency  on  the  part  of  his 
contributors  to  expatiate  unduly,  but  a  sort  of  waywardness  might 
be  expected.  One  would  not  be  surprised  to  find  Plato  setting 
down  his  thought  in  a  myth.  Augustine  might  wish  to  publish  an 
exhortation  and  Thomas  a  Kempis  a  pious  prayer.  I  am  inclined 
to  think  there  would  be  slighter  difficulty  with  the  German  con- 
tributors; for  after  all,  to  be  a  philosopher  in  Germany  is  to  have 
a  profession  and  to  recognize  professional  rules  and  etiquette. 

So  we  might  expect  to  find  in  this  history  of  contemporary 
German  philosophy,  to  which  each  of  the  writers  has  contributed 
his  own  statement  of  his  views  and  of  their  psychogenesis,  a  certain 
"cut  and  driedness."  Such  an  expectation  is,  however,  by  no  means 
justified  by  the  contents  of  the  volume.  There  is,  to  be  sure,  a 
noticeable  dominance  of  the  idol  of  the  system  over  certain  of  the 
contributors.  One  "decided  to  become  a  philosopher."  Another, 
when  he  was  called  to  an  academic  position,  discovered  that  he  was 
supposed  by  the  traditions  of  the  post  to  lecture  on  certain  subjects 
and  forthwith  began  to  do  so.  And  frequently  one  is  aware  that 
the  progress  of  a  man 's  thought  is  too  greatly  determined  by  a  sense 
of  obligation  to  fill  the  picture  previously  outlined,  or  to  expand 
his  theories  so  as  to  cover  every  portion  of  the  philosophic  field. 
It  is  altogether  probable  that  these  faults,  if  faults  they  be, 
are  due  to  the  fact  that  the  representatives  of  philosophy  whose 
views  are  here  given  are  principally  in  the  university  world  and  of 
the  philosophical  department.  One  is  glad  to  note  that  the  editor, 
Dr.  Raymund  Schmidt,  promises  that  future  volumes  will  also  con- 
tain a  presentation  of  authors  whose  contributions  lie  in  the  field  of 
the  philosophy  of  law,  of  education  and  other  departments.  Yet 
even  in  this  present  group  there  are  men  who  have  done  important 
work  outside  the  strict  limits  of  their  departmental  duties. 

Moreover,  one  is  struck  by  the  free  and  courageous  criticism 
which  a  man  of  the  stamp  of  Karl  Joel  directs  at  the  traditions 
of  university  teaching,  when  he  designates  lectures  as  "the  passive 
subjection  of  a  crowd  of  students  to  a  specialized  mass  of  material 
which  they  do  not  digest. ' '  The  editor  is  justified  in  his  promise  that 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

the  collection  will  consist  of  striking  contrasts.  The  men  whose 
contributions  constitute  the  first  volume  are  Paul  Barth,  Erich 
Becher,  Hans  Driesch,  Karl  Joel,  A.  Meinong,  Paul  Natorp,  Johannes 
Rehmke  and  Johannes  Volkelt ;  those  appearing  in  the  second  being 
Erich  Adickes,  Clemens  Baeumker,  Jonas  Cohn,  Hans  Cornelius, 
Karl  Groos,  Alois  Hofler,  Ernst  Troeltsch,  and  Hans  Vaihinger. 
There  is  no  need  to  make  invidious  comparisons;  they  are  a  distin- 
guished group.  The  absence  of  such  names  as  Rudolph  Eucken, 
Aloys  Riehl,  and  Ernst  Mach  may  cause  surprise,  particularly  since 
no  reason  is  given  for  their  omission. 

In  so  far  as  any  general  trend  is  noticeable  throughout  the 
work,  I  think  it  would  be  fair  to  interpret  it  as  a  return  to  the  older 
tradition  of  German  idealism.  Fortunately,  there  can  be  no  sus- 
picion that  this  is  due  to  the  editor's  selection,  for  Dr.  Schmidt  has 
indeed  adhered  scrupulously  to  his  above-mentioned  intention  of 
making  the  collection  a  genuine  symposium.  If  I  am  justified  in 
claiming  to  discover  the  renaissance  of  idealism,  it  is  surely  advisable 
to  spell  it  with  a  small  "i."  Yet  the  emphasis  is  unmistakable,  and 
is  manifest  in  the  motive  which,  for  instance,  has  led  Vaihinger,  and 
his  collaborators,  Groos  and  Cornelius,  to  reinterpret  the  Philosophic 
des  als  Ob  as  a  positivistic  idealism  in  which  the  Als-01)  world  be- 
comes the  world  of  values  more  especially  of  a  religious  order.  This 
interest,  so  clearly  reminiscent  of  ante-Hegelian  thought,  seems  to 
account  in  large  part  for  the  admirably  modest  recognition  of  the 
essentially  personal  aspects  of  problems  of  evaluation.  Undoubtedly 
it  also  accounts  for  the  importance  given  to  the  biographic  and  psy- 
chogenetic  conception  of  philosophy,  as  voiced  by  Fichte:  Was  fiir 
eine  Philosophic  man  wdhle,  hdngt  davon  ab,  was  filr  em  Mensch 
man  sei.  It  is  significant  that  this  sentence  is  quoted  several  times  in 
these  volumes. 

That  each  of  the  contributors  is  aware  of  a  certain  embarrassment 
in  speaking  of  himself  is  evident.  "De  nobis  ipsis  sttemus,"  Paul 
Natorp  begins — and  others  echo  the  sentiment.  They  are  over- 
anxious, in  numerous  instances,  to  avoid  self-advertisement.  "Ameri- 
canism" (sic),  is  discounted.  The  writers  recognize  that  they  can 
not  hope  properly  to  estimate  their  own  contributions  to  philosophic 
literature.  Meinong,  whose  contribution  is  unfortunately  a  final 
summary  of  his  views,  writes  thus  of  the  difficulty  of  the  undertak- 
ing— "When  one's  work  is  drawing  to  an  end,  the  question  may 
naturally  confront  one  as  to  what  one  has  accomplished  in  this 
brief  day  of  life.  But  if  he  as  genuinely  desires  to  answer  the 
question,  the  feeling  will  arise  that  he  can  only  conscientiously  give 
account  of  that  which  he  has  sought  to  do,  not  of  that  which  he  has 
achieved." 


306  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Each  article  is  preceded  by  a  photograph  of  the  author,  excellent 
in  craftsmanship  and  in  several  instances  striking  portraits.  The 
book  is  attractively  made,  though  the  economy  of  cloth  is  evident. 
One  wonders  who  in  Germany  can  afford  to  pay  sixty  marks  for  a 
volume,  though  at  the  present  rate  of  exchange,  it  is  considerably 
less  expensive  than  a  similar  book  would  be  in  this  country. 

JAMES  GUTMANN. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


JOUKNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

REVUE  PHILOSOPHIQUE.  Sept.-Oct.,  1921.  De  quelques 
especes  d'egalites  et  de  quelques-uns  de  leurs  wantages  ou  incon- 
venients  (pp.  146-172) :  ADRIEN  NAVILLE.-A  duality  of  conceptions 
of  equality  must  be  distinguished:  equality  of  contribution  in  ex- 
change, and  equality  of  individual  returns.  Equality  is  always  a 
psychical  fact,  and  sociologically  and  morally  it  is  not  the  case  that 
where  there  is  equality  of  contribution  in  exchange  there  is,  or  can  be, 
equality  of  return.  Justice  is  equality ;  but  there  are  many  varieties 
of  equality,  and  these  are  not  always  reconcilable.  La  perception  de 
la  synthese  psyctvique  (Suite:  pp.  173-191)  :  F.  PAULHAN.-WO 
' '  encounter  everywhere  in  conscious  life  the  perception  of  synthesis. 
It  constitutes  the  essential  element  in  the  control  of  the  mind  and  in 
the  control  of  its  elements.  .  .  .  The  perception  of  a  harmony  .  .  . 
or  a  discordance  is  continually  in  us,  and  this  is  the  knowledge  .  .  . 
and  appreciation  by  the  mind  and  its  elements  of  these  elements 
themselves  and  the  elements  of  these  elements."  Elements  objectifs 
du  monde  materiel  (Suite:  pp.  192-232)  :  P.  DuPONT.-The  point 
of  departure  for  science  after  stripping  away  every  human  element 
consists  of  relations  of  difference,  similarity  and  dissimilarity,  and 
the  like.  The  intellectual  character  of  these  relations  is  no  ground 
for  denying  objectivity.  No  photograph  of  the  objective  of  science 
can  be  given,  and  if  it  be  called  just  X,  it  can  be  shown  that  this  X 
"is  a  collection  of  a  multitude  of  x's  discriminable  by  us,"  and  the 
relations  between  them  can  be  firmly  established.  The  objective  of 
science  can  not  then  be  equated  with  nothingness.  La  notion  des 
centres  coordinateurs  cere~braux  et  le  mecanisme  du  langage  (suite: 
pp.  233-280) :  H.  PIERON.-'  '  The  progress  of  our  localizations  is  in- 
contestable ;  from  the  moment  that  we  no  longer  seek  to  localize  the 
entities,  imaginary  faculties,  and  judgments  of  value  .  .  .  and  all 
the  idola  of  traditional  psychology  and  expect  to  find  .  .  .  only  the 
histo-morphological  correspondents  of  psycho-physiological  processes 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  307 

analyzed  in  an  objective  spirit,  we  encounter,  despite  evident  difficul- 
ties, no  insurmountable  obstacle  in  progress  towards  a  functional 
chart  of  the  brain."  Revue  Critique.  Philosophies  de  L'Orient: 
P.  MASSON-OURSEL,.  Analyses  et  Comptes  rendus.  P.  E.  B.  Jour- 
dain,  The  Philosophy  of  Mr.  B*tr*nd  R*ss*ll:  A.  LALANDE.  J. 
Segond,  Intuition  et  Amitie:  E.  LEROUX.  Ossip-Lourie,  La  Grapho- 
manie:  DR.  JEAN  PHILIPPE.  Hector  Denis,  Discours  philosophiques: 
C.  BOUGLE.  A.  Gemelli,  Religione  e  scienza;  F.  Olgiati,  Carlo  Marx; 
A.  Gemelli,  Le  dottrine  moderne  djslla  delinquenza:  E.  GILSON.  Dr. 
Ed.  Claparede,  L'ecole  sur  mesure:  E.  CRAMAUSSEL..  Paul  Lapie, 
Pedagogic  frangaise:  E.  CRAMAUSSEL.  Necrologie:  Francois  Picavet 
(1851-1921}. 

Prescott,  Frederick  Clarke.  The  Poetic  Mind.  New  York:  The 
Macmillan  Co.,  1922.  Pp.  xx  +  308.  $2.00. 

Sinclair,  May.  The  New  Idealism.  New  York :  The  Macmillan  Com- 
pany, 1922.  Pp.  333.  $3.00. 


AN  OPEN  LETTER  TO  THE  ANTI-BEHAVIORISTS 
Dear  Fellow  Workers: 

I  have  followed  your  papers  during  the  last  ten  years  with  keen 
interest  and  much  profit  and  now  at  the  end  of  the  decade  I  feel  im- 
pelled to  put  a  question  to  you.  At  first  blush  the  interrogation  may 
seem  personal  and  yet  I  assure  you  that  it  is  motivated  only  by  the 
most  dispassionate  search  for  truth  on  this  question  which  is  causing 
you  so  much  unrest.  It  may  well  be  that  a  little  self-analysis,  a 
little  effective  introspection  directed  at  a  certain  aspect  of  the  social 
situation  now  constituted  by  the  ' ' Behavioristic  Controversy"  may 
throw  just  that  light  upon  the  problem  which  will  enable  some  of 
us  to  cast  our  lot  definitely  with  one  party  or  the  other. 

I  want  to  ask  you  this:  "Who  are  the  behaviorists  ?  Have  you 
ever  brought  together  a  bibliography  of  this  topic  for  the  past 
decade?  If  you  have  not,  the  undertaking  will  be  most  enlightening. 
I  can  find  but  two  men  who  have  presented  and  defended  behavior- 
ism, Drs.  John  B.  Watson  and  A.  P.  Weiss.  Their  labors  are  summed 
up  in  two  books  and  some  dozen  papers.  I  can  not  admit,  as  you 
may  see,  that,  there  is  any  other  behaviorism  than  that  advocated  by 
Dr.  Watson.  Behaviorism  has  come  to  mean  just  one  thing  and 
that  is  a  psychology  which  takes  as  its  subject  matter,  not  con- 
sciousness, but  stimulus  and  response  relationships.  Some  of  you,  I 


308  JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

know,  have  advocated  new  systems  of  behaviorism,  but  you  do  not 
succeed.  No  one  in  writing  of  this  point  of  view  is  attacking  your 
system,  and  the  more  papers  you  write  the  more  firmly  do  you  fix 
the  true  historical  significance  of  the  term.  Your  "truly  psychologi- 
cal behaviorism,"  your  "new  formula,"  your  "conscious  behavior" 
and  the  other  substitutes  which  you  hasten  to  bring  forth,  only 
serve  to  direct  attention  to  the  illegitimate  nature  of  your  offspring. 
But  if  we  find  only  two  behaviorists  in  the  literature,  how  many  and 
what  anti-behavioriste  can  be  found!  For  fear  of  offending  some 
of  you  by  omission,  I  shall  not  urge  the  following  list  as  complete. 
It  is,  however,  fairly  so  and  certainly  is  quite  representative.  May 
I,  then,  present  the  following  antis :  James  R.  Angell,  E.  B.  Titchener, 
R.  M.  Yerkes,  B.  Bode,  M.  W.  Calkins,  Win.  McDougall,  A.  A. 
Robach,  D.  S.  Miller,  H.  R.  Marshall,  H.  R.  Crosland,  B.  C.  Tolman, 
A.  0.  Lovejoy,  J.  R.  Kantor,  Mrs.  DeLaguna,  M.  F.  Washburn,  E.  B. 
Holt,  George  Mead,  Bertrand  Russell,  T.  H.  Pear,  F.  C.  Bartlett, 
E.  M.  Smith,  G.  H.  Thompson,  A.  Robinson,  and  others.  I  do  not 
include  either  the  writers  of  text-books  or  scientists  other  than  psy- 
chologists; but  a  complete  roster  of  printed  opponents  would  range 
from  zoologists  to  philosophers  and  from  humble  members  to  presi- 
dents of  the  American  Psychological  Association.  Almost  each  new 
periodical  number  affords  a  "coming-out  party"  for  a  new  member 
of  your  group.  And  there  is  no  apparent  increase  among  your  op- 
ponents. 

My  dear  friends,  why  do  you  write  so  mucht  I  raise  the  issue 
in  all  seriousness.  If  here,  there,  and  yonder,  psychologists  were 
joining  Watson's  banner,  you  might  be  actuated  by  the  menace  of 
opposing  numbers.  But  if  behaviorism  is  spreading,  the  literature 
fails  to  reveal  it,  although  the  cloak  rooms  and  corridors  may  bear 
more  eloquent  witness.  I  will  not  be  so  vulgar  as  even  to  suggest 
that  your  articles  are  merely  for  the  sake  of  intellectual  exercise  and 
the  display  of  critical  skill.  No,  it  is  the  power  and  incisiveness  of 
the  theory  which  you  fear,  a  theory  which  without  increasing  de- 
fenders causes  you  to  see  an  enemy  in  every  one  not  an  anointed 
introspectionist  and  to  detect  a  danger  in  all  objective  study.  This 
social  phenomenon  affords  the  strongest  argument  inclining  me 
to  believe  that  Watson  has  found  the  Achilles  heel  of  your  "old" 
psychology. 

Ladies  and  gentlemen,  you  do  protest  too  much. 

Affectionately  yours, 

W.  S.  HUNTER. 
THI  UNIVERSITY  or  KANSAS. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  12  JUNE  8,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


REALISM  WITHOUT  MONISM  OR  DUALISM— I 
KNOWLEDGE  INVOLVING  THE  PAST 

TN  his  contribution  to  the  volume  of  Essays  in  Critical  Realism 
Professor  Lovejoy  maintains  that  pragmatism  can  make  good 
a  profession  of  realism  only  by  aligning  itself  with  a  dualistic  epis- 
temology  such  as  is  presented  by  his  collaborators  and  himself.  He 
supports  this  contention  largely  by  an  examination  of  passages 
drawn  from  my  writings.  The  least  I  can  do  is  either  to  express 
my  assent  or  state  the  grounds  for  witholding  it.  Certain  of  his 
points,  and  those  perhaps  of  the  more  fundamental  character,  though 
occupying  less  space,  concern  the  conception  of  experience.  This 
phase  of  the  matter  is  reserved  for  independent  treatment.  Other 
points  seem,  however,  to  adapt  themselves  to  separate  discussion, 
and  to  them  I  address  myself.  The  first  has  to  do  with  knowledge  of 
the  past,  or,  as  from  my  standpoint  I  should  prefer  to  say,  knowledge 
about  past  events  or  involving  them. 

This  kind  of  knowledge  is  taken  by  Mr.  Lovejoy,  as  by  many 
others,  to  constitute  a  stronghold  for  a  representative  or  dualistic 
theory  of  knowledge.  Even  the  monistic  epistemologists  appear  to 
accept  some  kind  of  transcendent  pointing  to  and  lighting  upon  some 
isolated  thing  of  the  past,  carrying,  apparently,  its  own  place  in  the 
past  or  date  in  its  bosom,  though  they  deny  the  existence  of  an  in- 
termediate psychical  state  and  fall  back  on  a  knower  in  general  or  a 
brain  process  to  make  the  specific  transcendent  reference.  To  me, 
this  latter  difference  seems  a  minor  matter  compared  with  the  ques- 
tion of  a  leap  into  a  past  which  is  treated  as  out  of  connection  with 
the  present.  Consequently,  I  have  tried  to  show  that  knowledge 
where  the  past  is  implicated  is  logically  knowledge  of  past-as-con- 
nected-with-present-or-future,  or  stating  the  matter  in  its  order,  of 
the  present  and  the  future  as  implicating  a  certain  past.  After 
several  pages  which  seem  to  me  largely  irrelevant  to  my  own  con- 
ception, Mr.  Lovejoy  states  what  my  conception  actually  is  and  says 
of  it  (p.  68)  that  it  is  "the  most  effective  and  plausible  part  of  the 
pragmatist's  dialectical  reasoning  against  the  possibility  of  strictly 
'retrospective'  knowledge."  It  certainly  should  be;  it  expresses 
the  gist  of  my  discussion. 

309 


310  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

The  point  concerns  the  relation  of  verification  to  thought  and 
hence  to  knowledge.  Verification  of  thought  about  the  past  must 
be  present  or  future;  unless,  then,  thought  about  the  past  has  a 
future  reference  in  its  meaning,  how  can  it  .be  verified  f  With  ref- 
erence to  this  question,  Mr.  Lovejoy  is  good  enough  to  state  that 
my  "paradox"  involves  an  attempt  to  escape  from  a  real  difficulty 
or  at  least  what  appears  as  a  difficulty.  Before  coming  to  Mr. 
Lovejoy 's  specific  objections,  let  me  develop  this  point.  Quite  apart 
from  pragmatism,  an  empiricist  who  is  empirical  in  the  sense 
of  trying  to  follow  the  method  of  science  in  dealing  with  natural 
existences,  will  feel  logically  bound  to  call  nothing  knowledge  which 
does  not  admit  of  verification.  To  him,  then,  judgments  about  the 
past  will  present  themselves  as  hypothetical  until  verified — which 
can  take  place  only  in  some  object  of  present  or  future  experience. 
In  contemplating  the  possibility  of  applying  this  conception  to 
ordinary  "memory-judgments,"  he  will  be  struck  by  what  is  going 
on  in  the  natural  sciences.  He  will  see  that  many  zoologists  have 
ceased  to  be  satisfied  with  theories  about  past  evolution  which  rest 
simply  upon  a  plausible  harmonizing  of  past  events,  that  they  are 
now  engaged  in  experimentation  to  get  present  results,  that  the 
tendency  is  to  find  present,  and  hence  observable,  processes  which 
determine  certain  consequences.-  He  finds  geologists  attempting 
verification  by  experiment  as  well  as  by  search  for  additional  facts. 
Turning  to  another  field  of  judgments  about  the  past  he  finds  that 
"literary"  historians  are  influenced  by  the  striking  or  picturesque 
or  moral  phases  of  the  events  they  deal  with,  and  by  their  lending 
themselves  to  composition  into  a  harmonious  picture,  while  "scien- 
tific" historians  are  not  only  more  scrupulous  about  the  facts,  but 
search  for  new,  as  yet  hidden,  facts,  to  bear  out  their  inferential 
reconstructions.  There  is  nothing  inherently  paradoxical  in  saying 
that  such  emphatic  scientific  cases  should  give  us  our  clew  to  under- 
standing the  logic  of  everyday  cases  which  are  not  scientifically  regu- 
lated. 

I  see  a  letter  box ;  there  is  an  observed  thing.  It  is  a  common- 
place that  every  recollection  starts,  directly  or  indirectly,  with  some- 
thing perceived,  immediately  present.  It  suggests  a  letter.  This 
may  remain  a  mere  suggestion.  The  thought  of  a  letter  written 
yesterday  or  last  year  may  become  simply  something  for  fancy  to 
sport  with — an  esthetic  affair,  what  I  call  a  reminiscence.  Truth 
or  falsity  does  not  enter  into  the  case.  But  it  may  give  rise  to 
questions.  Did  I  actually  write  the  letter  or  only  mean  to?  If  I 
wrote  it.  did  I  mail  it  or  leave  it  on  my  desk  or  in  my  pocket?  Then 
I  do  something.  I  search  my  pockets.  I  look  on  my  desk.  I  may 


REALISM  WITHOUT  MONISM  OR  DUALISM          311 

even  write  the  person  in  question  and  inquire  if  he  received  a  letter 
written  on  a  certain  date.  By  such  means  a  tentative  inference  gets 
a  categorical  status.  A  logical  right  accrues,  if  the  experiments  are 
successful,  to  assert  the  letter  was  or  was  not  written.  Generalize 
the  case  and  you  get  the  logical  theory  concerning  knowledge  about 
the  past  which  so  troubles  Mr.  Lovejoy.1 

So  far,  however,  the  gravamen  of  Mr.  Lovejoy 's  objection  is  not 
touched.  He  replies  that  the  meaning  of  the  judgment  concerns  the 
past  as  such,  so  that  verification  even  if  future  is  of  a  meaning  about 
the  past.  Only  the  locus  of  verification  is  future :  means  of  proof, 
but  not  the  thing  proved.  Consequently,  my  argument  confuses 
what  the  original  judgment  meant  and  knew  itself  to  mean  with  an 
extraneous  matter,  the  time  of  its  verification  (see  p.  69  of  E.  C.  R.). 
It  may  be  doubted  whether  dialectically  the  case  is  as  clear  as  Mr. 
Lovejoy 's  distinction  makes  it  out  to  be.  In  what  conceivable  way 
can  a  future  event  be  even  the  means  of  validating  a  judgment  about 
the  past,  if  the  meaning  of  the  future  event  and  the  meaning  of  the 
past  event  are  as  dissevered  as  Mr.  Love  joy's  argument  requires? 
Take  the  case  of  questions  about  the  past  which  are  intrinsically 
unanswerable,  at  least  by  any  means  now  at  our  command.  What  did 
Brutus  eat  for  his  morning  meal  the  day  he  assassinated  Csesar? 
There  are  those  who  call  a  statement  on  such  a  matter  a  judgment 
or  proposition  in  a  logical  sense.  It  seems  to  me  that  at  most  it  is 
but  an  esthetic  fancy  such  as  may  figure  in  the  pages  of  a  historic 
novelist  who  wishes  to  add  realistic  detail  to  his  romance.  Whence 
comes  the  intellectual  estoppal?  From  the  fact,  I  take  it,  that  the 
things  eaten  for  breakfast  have  left  no  consequences  which  are  now 
observable.  Continuity  has  been  interrupted.  Only  when  the  past 
event  which  is  judged  is  a  going  concern  having  effects  still  directly 
observable  are  judgment  and  knowledge  possible. 

The  point  of  this  conclusion  is  that  it  invalidates  the  sharp  and 
fixed  line  which  Mr.  Lovejoy  has  drawn  between  the  meaning  of  the 
past  and  the  so-called  means  of  verification.  So  far  as  the  meaning 
is  wholly  of  and  in  the  past,  it  can  not  be  recovered  for  knowledge. 
This  negative  consideration  suggests  that  the  true  object  of  a  judg- 
ment about  a  past  event  may  be  a  past-event-having-a-connection- 
continuing-into-the-present-and-future.  This  brings  us  back,  of 
course,  to  my  original  contention.  What  can  be  said  by  way  of  fact 
to  support  its  hypothetical  possibility? 

i  Mr.  Lovejoy  remarks  in  passing  that  "we  have  even  developed  a  tech- 
nique by  means  of  which  we  believe  ourselves  able  to  distinguish  certain  of  these 
representations  of  the  past  as  false  and  others  as  true"  (pp.  67-68  of  E.  C.  E.~). 
I  do  not  see  how  an  account  of  this  technique  could  fail  to  confirm  the  position 
taken  above;  I  am  willing  to  risk  it. 


312  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Let  us  begin  with  what  is  called  reminiscence.  The  tendency  to 
tell  stories  of  what  has  happened  to  one  in  the  past,  to  revive  interest 
ing  situations  in  which  one  has  figured,  is  a  well-known  fact.  So  far 
as  the  stories  are  told  to  illustrate  some  present  situation,  to  supply 
material  to  deal  with  some  present  perplexity,  to  get  instruction  or 
give  advice,  they  exemplify  what  is  said  about  prospective  meaning. 
But  there  are  only  a  few  persons  who  confine  themselves  to  what  is 
intellectually  pertinent,  who  cut  down  reminiscence  to  its  bare  logical 
bones.  Esthetic  interests  modify  the  tale,  and  personal,  more  or 
less  egoistic,  interests  fill  it  up  and  round  it  out.  The  development 
of  reminiscence  in  old  age  is  doubtless  in  part  compensatory  for 
withdrawal  from  the  actual  scene  and  its  imminent  problems,  its 
urgencies  for  action. 

Taking,  however,  whatever  intellectual  core  there  may  be,  such  as 
the  material  that  is  employed  to  give  advice  to  another  as  to  how 
to  deal  with  a  confused  and  unclear  situation,  there  appears  a  clear 
distinction  between  subject-matter  employed  and  object  meant.  The 
past  occurrence  is  not  the  meaning  of  the  propositions.  It  is  rather 
so  much  stuff  upon  the  basis  of  which  to  predicate  something  re- 
garding the  better  course  of  action  to  follow,  the  latter  being  the  object 
meant.  It  makes  little  difference  whether  the  past  episode  drawn 
upon  is  reported  with  literal  correctness  or  not.  Imagination  usually 
plays  with  it  and  in  the  direction  of  rendering  it  more  pertinent  to 
the  case  in  hand.  This  does  not  necessarily  affect  the  value  of  the 
judgment — the  advice  given — as  to  the  course  of  action  which  it  is 
better  to  pursue,  or  the  object  of  judgment.  The  facts  cited,  the 
illustrative  material  adverted  to  in  support  of  the  conception  that  a 
certain  course  is  better,  are  subject-matter,  but  not  the  meaning  or 
object. 

Such  a  case  does  not  directly  and  obviously  cover  judgments 
about  the  past.  If  the  one  giving  advice  began  to  reflect  upon  the 
pertinency  of  his  own  past  experience  to  the  new  issue,  we  may 
imagine  him  going  back  over  the  past  episode  to  judge  how  correctly 
he  has  reported  it.  Just  what  was  it  that  happened,  anyway  f 
This  sort  of  case  is  crucial  for  my  theory.  It  exemplifies  the  situation 
in  which  Mr.  Lovejoy  claims  that  the  meaning  to  be  verified  is  ex- 
clusively concerned  with  the  past  even  though  the  locus  of  means 
of  verification  be  future.  It  is  worthy  of  note  that,  by  illustration, 
this  examination  of  the  correctness  of  the  present  notion  about  the 
past  arises  out  of  a  problem  about  the  present  and  future.  It  is 
conceivable  that  specific  reference  to  the  past  is,  after  all,  only  part 
of  the  procedure  of  making  judgment  about  the  present  as  adequate 
as  possible. 


REALISM  WITHOUT  MONISM  OR  DUALISM          313 

This  point  is  not  stressed,  however,  for  it  is,  at  this  stage  of 
discussion,  an  easy  retort  that  such  an  inference  follows  only  because 
the  illustration  has  already  been  loaded  and  aimed  in  that  direction. 
As  a  suggestion,  however,  it  may  be  borne  in  mind.  What  does 
positively  emerge  from  the  prior  discussion  is  a  distinction  between 
subject-matter  and  object  of  judgment  and  knowledge.  How  far  is 
the  distinction  a  general  one  ?  It  is  not  one  introduced  ad  hoc  for 
the  discussion  of  judgments  about  the  past.  It  characterizes  by 
logical  necessity  any  inquiry.  For  if  the  object  were  present,  there 
would  be  no  inquiry,  no  thought  or  inference,  no  judgment  in  any 
intellectual  sense  of  that  word.  On  the  other  hand,  there  must  be 
subject-matter,  there  must  be  accepted  considerations,  or  else  there 
is  no  basis  for  constructing  or  discovering  the  object.  A  verdict 
represents  the  judgment  in  a  court  of  law ;  it  contains  the  object,  the 
thing  meant.  Evidence  presented  and  rules  of  law  applied  furnish 
subject-matter.  These  are  diverse  and  complicated  and  only  gradually 
is  the  object  framed  from  them.  A  scientific  inquiry  about  Einstein's 
theory,  the  nature  of  temperature,  or  the  cause  of  earthquakes  presents 
the  same  contrast  of  an  ultimate  object,  still  unattained  and  question- 
able, and  subject-matter  which  is  progressively  presented  and  sifted 
till  it  coheres  into  an  object,  when  judgment  terminates.2 

If  we  apply  this  generic  and  indispensable  distinction  to  analysis 
of  judgments  about  the  past,  it  seems  to  me  that  the  following  con- 
clusion naturally  issues:  The  nature  of  the  past  event  is  subject- 
matter  required  in  order  to  make  a  reasonable  judgment  about  the 
present  or  future.  The  latter  thus  constitutes  the  object  or  genuine 
meaning  of  the  judgment.  Take  the  illustration  of  the  letter.  Its 
object  must  be  described  in  some  such  terms  as  the  following.  What 
is  the  state  of  affairs  as  between  some  other  person  and  myself! 
Is  his  letter  acknowledged  or  no ;  is  the  deal  closed,  the  engagement 
made,  the  assurance  given  or  no?  The  only  subject-matter  which 
will  permit  an  answer  to  the  question  is  some  past  episode.  Hence 
the  necessity  of  coming  to  close  quarters  with  that  past  event.  In 
the  subject-matter  there  are  always  at  least  two  alternatives,  while 
the  object  is  singular  and  unmistakable.  Either  I  wrote  the  letter 
or  I  did  not.  Which  thought  or  hypothesis  is  correct?  There  can 
be  no  inquiry  without  just  such  incompatible  alternatives  present  to 
mind.  I  have  to  clear  up  the  question  of  what  is  the  object  of  judg- 
ment by  settling  its  appropriate  subject-matter :  what  has  happened. 
The  object  of  the  judgment  in  short  is  the  fulfillment  of  an  intention, 

2  Subject-matter  is  not  to  be  confused  with  data.  It  is  wider  than  data.  It 
includes  all  considerations  which  are  adduced  as  relevant,  whether  by  way  of 
factual  data  or  accepted  meanings,  while  data  signifies  such  facts  as  are  defi- 
nitely selected  for  employment  as  evidential. 


314  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

I  intended  or  meant  to  enter  into  certain  relations  with  a  correspon- 
dent. Have  I  done  so  or  is  the  matter  still  hanging  fire  t  Certainly, 
whether  or  not  my  analysis  is  correct,  there  does  not  appear  to  be 
anything  forced  or  paradoxical  about  the  view  that  in  all  such  cases 
the  actual  thing  meant,  the  object  of  judgment,  is  prospective.8 

To  protect  the  conclusion  from  appearing  to  depend  upon  the 
quality  of  the  particular  illustration  used,  namely  one  involving  a 
personal  past  and  personal  course  of  action,  we  need  an  impersonal 
instance  of  a  past  episode.  That  provided  by  Mr.  Lovejoy  may  be 
employed.  "When  I  point  to  this  morning's  puddles  as  proof  that 
it  rained  last  night,  the  puddles  are  the  means  of  proof  but  not  the 
thing  proved.  For  verification-purposes  their  sole  interest  to  me 
is  not  in  themselves,  but  in  what  they  permit  me  to  infer  about  last 
night's  weather.  If  someone  shows  me  that  they  were  made  by  the 
watering-cart,  they  become  irrelevant  to  the  subject-matter  of  my 
inquiry — though  the  same  proposition  about  the  future,  'there  will 
be  puddles  in  the  street,'  is  still  fulfilled  by  them"  (p.  69  of 
E.  C.  R.).  One  wishes  that  Mr.  Lovejoy  had  subjected  his  state- 
ment to  the  same  critical  scrutiny  to  which  he  has  exposed  mine. 
When  it  is  examined,  certain  interesting  results  present  themselves. 

In  the  first  place,  my  conception  is  not  contained  or  expressed 
by  any  such  judgment  as  that  "there  are  or  will  be  puddles  in  the 
street."  The  implication  of  my  hypothesis  is  that  the  object  of 
judgment  is  that  "prior  rain  has  present  and  future  conse- 
quences," such  as  puddles,  or  floods,  or  refreshment  of  crops,  or 
filling  of  cisterns,  etc.  In  denying  that  the  past  event  is  as  such 
the  object  of  knowledge,  it  is  not  asserted  that  a  particular  present 
or  future  object  is  its  sole  and  exhaustive  object,  but  that  the  content 
of  past  time  has  "a  future  reference  and  function."  *  That  is,  the 
object  is  some  past  event  in  its  connection  with  present  and  future 
effects  and  consequences.  The  past  by  itself  and  the  present  by 
itself  are  both  arbitrary  selections  which  mutilate  the  complete  ob- 
ject of  judgment.  What  appears  in  the  above  case  of  the  letter  as 
a  fulfilment  of  intention,  appears  here  as  a  temporal  sequence  of 
condition  and  consequence.  In  each  case,  the  past  incident  is  part 
of  the  subject-matter  of  inquiry  which  enters  into  its  object  only 
when  referred  to  a  present  or  future  event  or  fact. 

In  the  second  place,  analysis  reveals  that  the  proposition  "there 

3  The  argument  does  not  depend  upon  any  ambiguity  between  objective  and 
object.  As  long  as  inquiry  is  going  on  the  object  is  an  objective  because  it  is 
atill  dn  question.  The  final  object  represents  some  objective  taking  settled  and 
definitive  form. 

«  As  Mr.  Lovejoy  quotes  from  me.  (p.  67  of  E.  C.  22.).  I  do  not  wish  to 
daim,  however,  that  I  have  previously  made  this  point  as  clearly  as  I  am  now 
making  it. 


REALISM  WITHOUT  MONISM  OR  DUALISM          315 

will  be  puddles  in  the  street"  is  not  the  same  in  case  the  passage 
of  the  watering-cart  is  the  past  event  which  properly  enters  into 
the  subject-matter  of  inquiry.  It  is  by  further  investigation  of 
present  and  future  facts  that  it  is  determined  whether  a  watering- 
cart  or  a  shower  is  the  actual  past  event.  Not  all  streets  will  have 
puddles  if  the  watering-cart  was  the  cause,  or  at  least  roofs  won't 
be  wet,  cisterns  won't  be  replenished,  farmers'  soil  moistened.  If 
we  consult  the  value  of  accurate  weather  reports  to  a  mariner  or  a 
member  of  the  Chicago  Board  of  Trade,  we  get  light  upon  the  real 
object  of  a  judgment  involving  past  weather  conditions.  The  point 
is  the  connection  of  past-present-future,  a  temporal  continuum.  Pre- 
cisely to  avoid  such  incomplete  inferences  as  are  manifested  in  the 
conclusion  "there  will  be  puddles  in  the  street"  on  the  basis  of  con- 
siderations like  those  adduced  in  Mr.  Lovejoy's  illustration,  we 
make  the  exact  nature  of  the  past  event  the  theme  of  exact  and  scru- 
pulous inquiry.5  The  importance  of  the  present  as  basis  of  infer- 
ence about  the  past  is  seen  in  the  growing  importance  in  science  of 
contemporary  records,  registrations,  devices  for  carrying  over  the 
past  event  into  things  which  can  be  inspected  in  the  present,  devices 
for  measuring  and  registering  the  lapse  of  time,  etc.  This  makes  the 
difference  between  scientific  thought  and  loose  popular  thought. 
The  reference  to  or  connection  with  the  present  and  future  comes 
in  at  the  completing  end.  The  present  not  only  supplies  the  only 
data  for  a  correct  inference  about  the  past,  but  since  the  poten- 
tialities or  meanings  of  the  present  depend  upon  the  conditions  of 
the  past  with  which  they  are  correlated,  future  events  are  also 
implied  as  part  of  the  meaning.  If  a  watering-cart,  or  a  local 
shower,  then  no  effect  upon  crops,  no  effect  upon  the  prices  of  grain ; 
or,  on  a  lesser  scale,  no  needed  precautions  as  to  wearing  rubbers. 

The  logical  bearing  of  the  earlier  reference  (p.  311)  to  the  im- 
possibility of  judgments  about  the  past  without  continuing  and  present 
consequences  ought  now  to  be  clearer.  My  analysis  may  be  correct 
or  incorrect :  that  is  a  question  of  fact.  But  the  account  given  does 
not  involve  an  arbitrary  paradox  undertaken  in  behalf  of  some  pet 
theory.  The  real  point  at  issue  is  whether,  as  long  as  we  are  deal- 
ing with  isolated,  self-sufficient  events  or  affairs,  anything  which  is 
properly  called  knowledge  and  object  of  knowledge  can  exist.  The 
real  point  of  Mr.  Lovejoy's  argument  is  that  isolated,  self-complete 
things  are  truly  objects  of  knowledge.  My  theory  denies  the  validity 
of  this  conception.  It  asserts  that  mere  presence  in  experience  is 
quite  a  different  matter  from  knowledge  or  judgment,  which  always 
involves  a  connection,  and,  where  time  enters  in,  a  connection  of 

8  That  is,  we  examine  present  things  more  carefully  and  extensively. 


316  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

past  with  past  and  future.  The  reader  may  not  accept  this  theory,  in 
spite  of  its  congruity  with  all  the  best  authenticated  cases  of  knowl- 
edge of  matter  of  fact,  namely,  the  objects  of  science.  But  when  the 
secondary  matter  of  inconsistency  or  arbitrary  paradox  is  concerned, 
it  is  essential  to  grasp  this  point.  The  case  of  judgment  involving 
past  events  is  but  one  case  of  the  general  (logical)  theory  as  to  knowl- 
edge. And  as  I  have  pointed  out  before,  it  makes  it  possible  to  drop 
out  the  epistemological  theory  of  mysterious  "transcendence,"  and 
deal  with  problems  on  the  basis  of  objective  temporal  connections  of 
events,  where  we  never  are  obliged,  even  in  judgments  about  the 
remotest  geological  past,  to  get  outside  events  capable  of  future  and 
present  consideration.  Once  recognize  that  thoughts  about  the  past 
hang  upon  present  observable  events  and  are  verified  by  future 
predicted  or  anticipated  events  which  are  capable  of  entering  into 
direct  presentation,  and  the  machinery  of  transcendence  and  of 
epistemological  dualism  (or  monism)  is  in  so  far  eliminated. 

What  is  the  alternative  to  my  conception  ?  Mr.  Lovejoy  makes  it 
clear  what  the  alternative  is.  After  all,  we  have  not  got  very  far  when 
we  have  postulated  a  psychical  somewhat  that  somehow  transcends 
itself  and  leaps  back  into  the  past.  How  do  we  know  that  it  is  not 
leaping  into  the  air  or  into  some  quite  wrong  past  ?  In  speaking  of 
this  point,  and  denying  the  possibility  of  fulfilling  meanings  about 
the  past,  or  of  their  verification  proper,  he  mentions  ' '  an  irresistible 
propensity  to  believe  that  some  of  them  are  in  fact  valid  meanings" 
(p.  70,  italics  mine).  An  irresistible  propensity  which  applies  to 
"some"  meanings  and  not  to  others  is,  to  say  the  least,  a  curious 
fact.  It  suggests  that  perhaps  the  propensity  is  most  unreliable 
when  it  is  most  irresistible.  He  speaks  also  of  indirect  verification 
based  on  "instinctive  assumptions"  (p.  71).  He  says  that  a  truly 
pragmatic  analysis  "would  include  an  enumeration  of  the  not-im- 
mediately-given-things which  it  is  needful  for  the  effective  agent,  at 
that  moment,  to  believe  or  assume  ...  if  the  process  of  reflection  is 
to  be  of  any  service  to  him  in  the  framing  of  an  effective  plan  of 
action"  (p.  70).  He  charges  me  as  a  pragmatist  of  failing  to  live 
up  to  pragmatism  and.  "trying  to  transcend  one  of  the  most  inescap- 
able limitations  of  human  thought"  (p.  70). 

There  are  pragmatists  who  fall  back  on  instinctive  assumptions 
and  propensities,  as  a  ground  for  accepting  and  asserting  meanings 
to  be  valid.  They  will  welcome  Mr.  Lovejoy  to  the  fold.  But  the 
author  of  "Thirteen  Varieties  of  Pragmatism"  should  be  cognizant 
that  there  is  a  variety  not  of  the  "will  to  believe"  type.  If  his 
conception  is  such  a  fixed  part  of  the  definition  of  pragmatism  that 
refusing  to  admit  it  is  inconsistent  with  pragmatism,  then,  as  I  have 


DIFFERENTIATING  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELIGION       317 

said  before,  I  have  no  claim  to  be  called  a  pragmatist.  I  am  even 
hopeful  that  his  clear  statement  of  instinctive  propensity  versus 
logical  verification  as  the  alternatives  will  help  convert  some  non- 
pragmatists  to  my  account  of  knowledge  involving  past  events. 

Enumeration  of  the  things  needful  to  assume  in  framing  an  effec- 
tive plan  of  action  is  an  undoubted  part  of  the  process.  But  it  is  a 
hypothetical  enumeration.  Part  of  the  operation  of  intelligent  for- 
mation of  a  plan  of  action  is  to  note  what  the  needs  of  the  situation 
are.  But  the  needs  of  an  agent  can  themselves  be  judiciously  esti- 
mated only  in  connection  with  other  matters  which  enter  into  the 
situation  along  with  the  agent.  To  isolate  the  needs  or  propensities 
of  the  agent  and  regard  them  as  grounds  of  belief  in  the  validity  of 
meaning  seems  to  be  the  essence  of  subjectivism.  And  when  the 
plan  of  action  is  framed  it  is  still  tentative.  It  is  verified  or  con- 
demned by  its  consequences.  A  propensity  without  doubt  suggests 
a  certain  view  and  plan :  when  employed  in  connection  with  environ- 
ing factors  it  makes  a  view  or  plan  worthy  of  acceptance  for  trial, 
acceptance  as  a  working  hypothesis.  Beyond  this  point,  the  notion 
that  a  propensity,  however  practically  irresistible,  or  an  assumption, 
however  instinctive — if  there  be  such  things  apart  from  habit — war- 
rants belief  that  a  meaning  is  valid  commits  us  to  a  subjectivism 
which  is,  to  my  mind,  the  most  seriously  objectionable  thing  in 
idealism. 

It  is  Mr.  Love  joy,  it  seems  to  me,  who  is  committed  to  a  subjective 
pragmatism. 

JOHN  DEWEY. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


THE  DIFFERENTIATING  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELIGION 

THE  most  common  conception  of  religion  that  has  formed  the 
basis  of  theological  definition  is  that  which  general- 
izes man 's  total  outlook  upon  the  world  as  a  whole.  This  view,  which 
assumes  that  the  sphere  of  religion  and  the  world  are  commeasurable, 
is  chargeable  to  a  deeply  rooted  fear  that  some  vital  element,  essential 
to  the  fulness  of  spiritual  experience,  may  be  omitted  if  religion  is 
defined  exclusively  in  any  specific  phase  of  devotional  activity.  The 
complexity  of  the  religious  consciousness  appears  to  prohibit  any 
exemption  in  the  spiritual  sphere;  which  is  to  say,  religion  insists 
upon  being  as  inclusive  as  life  itself.  Consequently,  suspicion  or  un- 
popularity is  usually  associated  with  attempts  at  simplification,  such 
as  basing  religion  fundamentally  in  emotion,  or  belief,  or  will  or  any 
single  element  for  which  priority  is  claimed.  The  widest  and  most 


318  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

inclusive  view  of  the  world  in  its  totality  and  completeness  is  the 
conception  which  has  met  with  the  greatest  favor  in  the  minds  of 
those  to  whom  we  owe  our  standardized  definitions. 

But  this  determination  to  maintain  a  religious  monopoly  upon  the 
universe  has  strained  to  the  breaking  point  our  intellectual  con- 
scientiousness ;  for  an  average  amount  of  reflection  will  make  it  clear 
that  those  who  have  sought  to  define  the  nature  of  religion  specifi- 
cally in  terms  of  fear,  or  wonder,  or  reverence,  or  love,  or  any  other 
simple  element,  though  they  have  failed  in  exactness,  have  been  at 
any  rate  upon,  the  right  track,  since  religion  and  life  can  not  be  said 
to  coalesce  at  all  points  and  the  object  of  definition  is  differentia- 
tion. That  which  is  richest  in  universality  is  proportionately  poorer 
in  elucidation. 

In  order  to  survey  the  extent  of  the  religious  field  and  estimate 
how  wide  a  realm  lies  under  spiritual  control,  we  should  begin  by 
determining  the  fixed  center  of  spiritual  gravity,  so  to  speak,  for 
the  circumference  is  an  ever-shifting  circle.  It  is  impossible  to 
measure  the  boundaries  of  the  religious  realm  once  for  all,  but  it  is 
possible  and  necessary  to  determine  the  principle  that  obtains  in  all 
true  religion.  The  world  of  human  experience  is  an  ever-widening 
one  and  it  is  a  natural  error  to  conceive  the  province  of  religion  as 
constantly  enlarging  to  keep  pace  with  this  expansion,  but  in  reality 
the  reverse  is  true.  Modern  thought  is  fully  alive  to  the  need  of  a 
practical  evaluation  of  spiritual  reals,  an  evaluation  which  is  bound 
to  reduce  the  scope  of  religious  activities  to  decidely  narrow,  and 
more  and  more  exclusive  boundaries.  In  other  words,  the  world  is 
becoming  less  quantitatively  spiritual  than  ever  before,  and  this 
fact  suggests  the  need  of  establishing  more  precisely  than  has  yet 
been  done  with  any  degree  of  confidence  the  nature  of  the  differen- 
tiating principle  which  marks  off  the  specific  realm  of  genuine  re- 
ligion from  other  parts  of  existence. 

Let  me  recall  some  ways  in  which  religion  has  been  narrowed 
down.  The  Platonic  inheritance  of  the  Good,  the  True  and  the 
Beautiful,  appropriated  by  Christianity  as  permanent  apartments 
of  the  religious  sphere,  is  being  annulled  and,  in  fact,  is  already 
practically  spent.  The  fields  of  art,  truth  (philosophic) — not  to  men- 
tion science — have  long  overpast  the  boundaries  of  religious  con- 
trol. In  the  beginning,  science  was  subdued  somehow,  though  awk- 
wardly, art  was  more  gracefully  submissive,  and  truth  (i.e., 
Truth  semel  pro  semper)  became  more  or  less  the  faithful  handmaid 
of  theology;  and  this  religious  inclusiveness  went  along  with  the 
general  cosmic  idea  of  Deity  whose  omnipotent  sway  knew  no  bounds 
or  limitations.  This  traditional  all-embracing  view,  however,  has 


DIFFERENTIATING  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELIGION       319 

been  conspicuously  modified  in  recent  years.  Science  pursues  a  free 
course,  art  is  independent  of  religious  control,  truth  already  has 
gained  a  large  degree  of  functional  liberty,  and  morals,  always  rest- 
less and  impatient  of  spiritual  restraint,  would  seem  to  be  striving 
to  throw  off  the  religious  yoke  and  attain  the  freedom  which  science 
enjoys. 

Without  debating  the  relative  merits  of  the  good,  the  true,  the 
beautiful  and  the  dynamic  to  achieve  independence  in  their  respec- 
tive fields,  it  is  obvious  that  religion  must  forego  her  claim  of  absolute 
inclusiveness  and  recognize  legitimate  limitations.  And  if  the  signs 
of  the  times  are  truly  discerned,  one  may  conclude  that  religion,  her- 
self, is  not  loth  to  surrender  the  idea  of  cosmic  universality  in  ex- 
change for  one  that  is  more  intensive  and  less  abstract. 

Such  a  radical  tendency  or  change  in  spiritual  activities  has  been 
brought  about  in  the  following  way.  Before  the  study  of  compara- 
tive religion  had  become  an  accepted  part  of  Christian  apologetic — 
in  relatively  recent  times — it  was  the  custom  to  classify  world 
religions  according  to  a  general  standard  as  true  or  false,  Christian- 
ity in  some  form  or  other  being  set  off  against  all  other  systems  of 
faith  as  the  truth,  the  rival  beliefs  being  gauged  as  false,  or  at  any 
rate  merely  more  or  less  true — certainly  less.  To-day,  however,  this 
formal  system  of  classification  has  been  discarded,  and  we  are  in- 
clined, quite  universally,  to  formulate  a  system  of  classification  upon 
a  scale  of  the  better  and  the  worse  or  according  to  a  principle  of 
practical  value.  Instead  of  rating  the  so-called  world  religions  out- 
side Christianity  as  though  they  were  not  religions  at  all,  in  the  strict 
sense  of  the  word,  since  they  are  not  wholly  true,  we  are  willing  to 
admit  that  non-Christian  beliefs  and  practises  are  expressive  of 
religion,  qua  religion,  only  not  so  good,  not  so  high  and  pure,  not 
so  valuable,  functionally,  as  the  dominant  faith  of  the  world  to-day. 

This  change  of  mind  testifies  to  an  important  modification  of  our 
idea  of  the  nature  of  religion,  the  essence  of  which  is  thought  to  in- 
here in  that  which  constitutes  value  for  moral  and  spiritual  life.  Re- 
ligious practise  is  no  longer  judged  with  reference  to  the  truth  of  a 
belief  simply,  but  is  determined  by  a  criterion  of  value  or  worth ; 
and  belief,  itself,  is  expressed  more  and  more  in  terms  of  a  practical 
nature.  All  the  world  cults,  therefore,  are  recognized  for  what  they 
are  worth ;  and  all  successful  missionary  efforts  are  based  upon  this 
recognition.  Consequently  we  speak  of  one  form  of  religion  as  better 
than  another  or  a  particular  element  as  less  good  than  another;  the 
criterion  of  truth  is  relegated  to  second  place  and  the  principle  of 
value  or  goodness  prevails.  The  result  is  that  religion  becomes  ex- 
clusive inasmuch  as  she  limits  herself  to  that  which  is  the  highest 


320  JO  URNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

and  best,  and  in  the  interest  of  the  greater  values  she  eliminates  the 
lesser  and  irrelevant.  What  a  departure,  then,  from  the  position 
of  thinkers  in  the  time  of  Mill  who  wrote,  "If  religion,  or  any  par- 
ticular form  of  it  is  true,  its  usefulness  follows  without  any  other 
proof/'1 

To  realize  that  the  best  religion  must  inevitably  become  increas- 
ingly finite,  i.e.,  restricted  in  scope  and  limited  in  function,  may  ap- 
pear at  first  to  be  radically  opposed  to  the  commonly  cherished  ideal 
of  religion's  primacy  and  the  catholicity  of  spiritual  aims.  But  is 
this  the  case?  I  venture  to  suggest  that  the  reverse  is  tme.  Can 
not  religion,  as  a  palpable  ideal  and  an  actual  driving  force,  succeed 
better  in  the  dissemination  and  conservation  of  the  good  by  an  intensi- 
fication of  power  through  the  limitation  of  her  range? 

The  problem,  therefore,  that  arises  is  this :  If  religion  in  the  only 
form  now  acceptable  to  us  is  only  a  part  of  life  and  no  longer  the 
constitutive  principle  of  the  whole,  what  part  does  she  concentrate 
upon  and  in  ?  Such  a  question  is  the  direct  consequent  of  our  depart- 
ure from  a  crumbling  traditional  position  which  accepted  or  rejected 
spiritual  contributions  according  to  a  principal  of  standardized  truth. 
In  other  words,  inasmuch  as  we  now  employ  various  practical  gauges 
of  value  to  test  the  relevancy  of  religious  ideals  to  moral  and  spirit- 
ual ends,  we  are  bound  to  consider  religion  from  the  exclusive  point 
of  view,  and  ask:  What  elements  have  lost  their  original  spiritual 
value  ?  or,  What  factors  should  be  discarded  as  never  having  had  suf- 
ficient genuine  spiritual  worth  to  justify  their  survival?  That  is 
to  say,  we  are  narrowing  down  the  circle  of  the  religious  sphere,  and 
leaving  more  and  more  of  life  to  the  non-religious  field.  The  question 
remains  then:  What  survivals  are  essential  for  spiritual  progress? 

Before  I  attempt  to  state  my  thesis  in  answer  to  this  problem, 
let  me  emphasize  again  the  necessity  of  the  factor  of  religious  elim- 
ination. The  primary  tendency  or  instinct  of  organisms  to  develop 
from  the  simple  to  the  complex,  from  the  general  to  the  particular, 
from  the  single  to  the  plural  is  coordinate  with  a  law  of  progress 
which  organizes  by  a  process  of  elimination.  Steps  of  tho  advance 
can  usually  be  discerned  by  the  lopping  off  of  valueless  survivals. 
The  broader  syntheses  through  nature's  analytical  working,  com- 
parison, selection,  and  ever-renewed  coordination,  are  resolved  into 
more  centralized  and  richer  organizations.  And  human  naturt,  like- 
wise, refines  itself  by  specification.  Along  with  the  process  of  dif- 
ferentation,  integral  contractions  take  place  wherein  the  less  good 
gives  way  to  the  better  as  values  are  estimated  according  to  the  pur- 
posive workings  of  the  organism.  Man  realizes  himself  more  per- 

i  Cf.  Three  Essays  on  Religion,  p.  69. 


DIFFERENTIATING  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELIGION       321 

fectly,  i.e.,  successfully,  as  he  becomes  acquainted  with  himself  com- 
positely,  in  detail,  aware  of  mixed  and  combating  motives,  varied 
and  crossed  sentiments,  of  the  pluralistic  situation  within  himself. 
But  to  advance  means  to  refine,  i.e.,  to  judge,  choose  and  discard. 
In  the  end,  consciousness,  as  a  self-principle,  is  more  and  more  ex- 
elusive  in  relation  to  the  ever-increasing  richness  of  experience ;  and 
character  necessitates  constant  revaluation  and  reconstruction  in 
order  to  maintain  its  intrinsic  worth. 

The  religious  man  attains  the  highest  unity,  not  at  the  sacrifice 
of  the  elemental  multiplicity  of  experience,  but  at  the  sacrifice  of 
what  he  is  unwilling  to  identify  with  himself ;  he  is  more  concretely 
an  individual,  not  at  the  expense  of  experimental  experience,  but  at 
the  cost  of  what  he  refuses  to  incorporate  into  himself ;  he  is  a  more 
unique  personality,  not  because  appreciations  are  limited  or  pioneer 
adventures  are  shirked,  but  on  account  of  his  persistent  determina- 
tion to  ally  himself  only  with  the  highest  and  best  things  in  the 
world.  The  religious  man,  in  other  words,  is  intensively  and  in- 
tegrally good  because  he  dispenses  with  the  less  worthy  in  order  to 
concentrate  upon  that  which  alone  is  worth  the  greatest  effort.  In 
brief,  the  best  man  is  specifically  good;  there  is  an  originality  in 
his  goodness,  and  a  manifest  moral  partiality  in  his  estimate  and 
appropriation  of  values.  If  "he  sets  his  teeth"  in  the  not-self  of 
his  environment,  he  will  not  bite  off,  or  rather,  he  will  not  swallow, 
what  the  best  of  him  can  not  digest  and  assimilate  properly. 

Such  a  specification  of  virtue  is  the  inevitable  result  of  moral 
activities  within  the  particular  station  of  the  individual.  No  one 
person  can  have  a  monopoly  of  the  virtues ;  and  if  it  were  possible, 
he  would  be  able  to  exercise  but  those  which  pertained  to  his  own 
peculiar  office  and  vocation.  Consequently  we  see  the  soldier  con- 
spicuous for  courage,  the  economist  for  prudence,  the  student  for 
intellectual  integrity,  the  man  of  average  ability  for  temperance, 
the  prophet  for  spiritual  insight,  the  priest  for  piety  and  so  on.  A 
harmony  of  all  the  virtues,  coordinated  and  organized,  such  as  Plato 
delineated  in  the  Phcedrus  under  the  picture  of  the  charioteer  who 
drove  the  passions  courageously  and  prudently  is  practically  obsolete 
as  an  ideal  because  of  the  unreal  abstractions  involved  in  the  con- 
ception. The  real  man  exercises  and  perfects  only  those  virtues 
which  are  applicable  to  his  own  personal  situation.  It  may  be  con- 
cluded, then,  that  personality  grows  and  is  shaped  according  as  it 
excludes  all  factors  which  contribute  nothing  to,  or  would  detract 
from,  the  dominant  purpose  controlling  specific  self-realization. 

If  this  brief  sketch  of  the  extension  and  intension  of  human  per- 
sonality is  true  in  the  main,  may  we  not  unhesitatingly  believe  that  the 


322  JO  URNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

progress  of  religion  will  follow  much  the  same  lines  ?  Some  religious 
material  will  be  dropped  naturally  from  time  to  time  as  it  is  out- 
grown and  outworn,  and  the  rules  of  this  elimination  will  be  subject 
to  a  principle  of  discrimination.  What  this  principle  is,  is  exactly 
the  subject  of  our  enquiry.  When  we  see  that  one  religion  excels 
another,  that  certain  elements  are  obviously  more  valuable  than 
others,  and  that  many  survivals  have  become  worthless  and  must  ac- 
cordingly be  dispensed  with  as  irrelevant  or  incompatible  with  the 
more  important  factors,  then  the  problem  arises :  What  is  the  stand- 
ard gauge?  It  is  the  answer  to  this  question  which  will  nicely  de- 
termine the  exact  field  of  religion. 

Let  us  see  what  actual  signs  point  to  the  growing  exclusivene*s 
of  religion,  in  what  way  the  secular  realm  is  being  enlarged  for 
greater  gain  to  that  which  constitutes  the  essential  quality  of  spirit- 
ual life.  For  example,  then,  what  we  shall  eat,  what  we  shall  drink, 
what  we  shall  wear,  how  we  shall  plant  our  fields,  how  we  shall  build 
our  temples,  what  we  shall  teach,  what  books  shall  be  written  and  the 
thousand  and  one  details  over  which  in  the  past  religion  exercised  and 
exorcised  her  autocratic  say  are  now  excluded  from  the  province  of 
the  best  religious  faith  and  practise.  We  have  offered  the  purely 
material  and  mechanical  field  to  science  that  religion  may  gain 
the  more  freedom  in  her  own  realm ;  we  have  allowed  the  philosopher 
freer  play  in  the  realm  of  truth,  permitted  art  a  greater  liberty  in 
the  region  of  the  beautiful,  surrendered  to  psychology  the  secrets 
of  our  inner  life,  to  sociology  matters  of  organization,  to  the  state, 
matters  of  law — all  that  religion  may  enrich  herself  more  speedily 
after  her  special  liking.  We  have  sold  all,  or  almost  all,  we  possess 
for  the  one  jewel  of  great  price ;  we  pay  the  greater  price  to  Caesar 
that  God  may  receive  the  purer  treasure.  If,  then,  religion  abandons 
much  of  her  wonder  to  philosophy  and  much  of  her  miracle  to 
science  and  many  personal  mysteries  to  psychology,  and  surrenders 
her  beauty  largely  to  art,  her  organization  and  statutes  to  sociology 
and  economics,  the  importance  of  what  she  refuses  to  relinquish  is 
quite  obvious. 

The  answer  now  to  our  problem  is  not  difficult  to  see ;  but  do  we 
realize  what  this  means  or  is  going  to  mean  to  the  future  of  religion  ? 
The  final  stronghold  of  religion  being  moral  life,  toward  which  end 
all  present  religious  movements  are  conspicuously  pointing,  is  this. 
an  inspiring  sign  of  the  times  or  a  weakness  in  modern  spirituality  ? 
I  venture  to  state  that  this  pressure  upon  and  centralizing  in  morali- 
ties is  beyond  praise  and  must  prove  a  source  of  unlooked-for  hope 
in  these  troublous  times ;  for  the  moral-religious  merger  means  a  new 
vision  of  human  character  transcending  the  present  form  of  our 


DIFFERENTIATING  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELIGION       323 

ethos  and  all  out  of  proportion  with  its  development  hitherto,  as 
well  as  a  fresh  glory  for  religion  in  bringing  heaven  down  to  earth. 

It  is,  therefore,  in  this  special  field,  morality  in  its  widest  con- 
notation, that  we  see  religion  crowding  back  and  the  portent  is  mo- 
mentous. And  just  here  in  spite  of  the  dangerous  forces  which  have 
assaulted  the  fair  moral  stature  of  humanity,  if  the  most  trustworthy 
signs  of  the  times  are  to  be  accredited,  religion  appears  to  be  easily 
holding  her  own.  She  can  not  and  will  not  permit  a  trade  or  sport 
in  the  moral  nature  of  mankind.  We  have  sadly  learned  nostro 
periculo  that  a  large  measure  of  personality  is  not  equivalent  with 
goodness.  Individual  self-realization  or  community-realization  is 
attended  with  the  greatest  dangers  of  distortion  when  divorced 
from  spiritual  control.  The  horrible  fact  of  dgemonic  personality  is 
only  too  well  disclosed  by  the  ruthlessness  of  "civilized"  warfare. 
We  have  beheld  with  moral  terror  the  dispassionate  elimination  of 
all  that  unfits  a  person  for  the  achievement  of  his  ends  and  the  com- 
mon ends  of  his  fellows  regardless  of  a  scale  of  values  which  should 
determine  the  better  and  the  worse,  resulting,  not  simply  in  the  crime 
of  a  renaissance  of  barbaric  civilization,  but  in  something  more  in- 
tolerable, namely,  the  felonious  act  of  producing  the  personality  of 
the  savage — and  not  the  mere  savage,  unintellectual  and  cruel,  rather 
the  savage  as  an  ideal,  as  the  amoral  apotheosis  of  force. 

Strange  as  it  may  sound,  we  must  admit  that  the  incorrigible 
enemies  of  peace  are  idealists.  Ideals,  when  genuine,  are  intimate, 
individualistic  and  unique ;  which  is  to  say,  ideals  are  nothing  if  not 
a  matter  of  singular  personality.  They  are  the  stuff  that  is  naturally 
radical  and  wilful.  Hence  the  danger  lies  exactly  here:  the  fact 
that  it  is  the  instinctive  tendency,  the  whim,  the  spirit  of  an  ideal 
to  have  its  fling,  to  play  truant,  to  adventure  into  romance,  to  for- 
sake the  familiar  in  search  of  the  unfamiliar  in  ways  remote.  In 
other  words,  ideals  are  the  flower  of  moral  abstractions ;  they  sprout 
and  flourish  upon  a  stock  of  truth  which  grows  out  of  the  philosophic 
or  metaphysical  mind ;  they  delight  an  ambitious  imagination  with  an 
intoxicating  fragrance  until  nothing  can  withstand  them — nothing 
but  the  hard  facts  of  life  and  the  opposition  of  other  ideals.  It  fol- 
lows, then,  that  because  of  the  superior  force  of  idealistic  energies 
they  require  the  special  discipline  of  the  most  practical  judgments 
of  value  that,  religion  can  formulate,  or  character  is  ruined. 

To  supply  this  standard  of  personal  worth  is  the  rationale  of 
religion.  And  such  is  the  moral  emergency  of  the  present-day  world. 
It  is  exactly  at  this  point  and  with  this  definite  end  in  view  that  re- 
ligion enters  the  social  conflict.  All  of  which  suggests  the  differenti- 
ating feature  of  religion,  namely,  moral  interests.  In  this  field, 


324  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

religion  must  continue  to  exercise  and  maintain  her  peculiar  power, 
to  magnetize  the  moral  compass,  to  spiritualize  ideals,  to  gauge  the 
perfect  measure  of  the  right.  Morality  is  the  child,  religion  the 
parent;  but  forever  "the  child  is  father  to  the  man." 

The  antithesis  of  the  Christian  standard,  which  I  have  tried  to 
do  justice  to,  along  modern  lines,  is  that  of  the  orthodox  Pharisee, 
a  product  of  the  inclusiveness  of  later  Judaism  with  its  rigid  law. 
The  wonderful  moral  impetus  given  to  Old  Testament  religion  by 
the  prophetic  analysis  of  the  better  and  the  worse,  of  the  good  and 
the  evil,  of  the  righteous  and  the  wicked,  was  neutralized  and  blocked 
by  this  type  of  religious  inclusiveness.  The  curious  anomaly  of  the 
Pharisee,  viz.,  a  separateness  from  worldliness  combined  with  an 
attempt  to  bring  all  of  life  completely  within  the  compass  of  the 
Law,  presents  a  picture  of  religious  inclusion.  This  "separateness" 
from  the  world  was  a  contradictio  in  adjecto  to  the  rule  of  life  pro- 
fessed and  a  shallow  unreality.  The  truth  of  the  matter  is  that  the 
Pharisees  identified  worldliness  after  all  with  religion.  And  this 
was  precisely  the  trouble.  His  religion  was  too  inclusive ;  it  had  no 
distinct  character  which  permitted  the  functioning  of  comparative 
values ;  so  that  there  was  no  better  and  worse,  no  greater  command- 
ment, in  his  conception  of  moral  and  spiritual  life.  All  was  con- 
stituted on  the  same  level,  the  dead  level,  so  to  speak. 

It  is  in  this  sense  that  modern  religion  may  be  characterized  as 
finite;  because  of  a  specialization  in  moralities.  If  we  are  willing 
to  withdraw  from  other  fields,  it  is  because  there  is  one  pearl  of  great 
price  which  absorbs  all  our  enthusiasm ;  and  though  this  fine  spirit- 
ual exclusiveness  may  involve  the  abandonment  of  some  long-cher- 
ished cosmic  beliefs  and  the  difficult  sacrifice  of  many  dear  hopes, 
and  though  haunting  clouds  of  darkness  may  hover  over  the  unex- 
plored ground  where  ultimately  religion  and  morals  meet,  still  no 
truly  loving  heart  need  fear  self-deception  when  the  spirit  of  Christ 
manifest  in  any  good  action  whatsoever  is  identified  with  Christ 
himself.  For  love  is  the  most  accurate  moral  compass  with  which 
human  nature  is  endowed. 

In  this  highly  specialized  and  highly  secularized  world  of  ours — 
rightly  so — our  alarm  at  the  loss  of  much  that  had  been  thought  to 
belong  indissolubly  to  religion,  which  is  now  being  withheld  from 
her  without  protest,  may  be  assuaged  by  recollecting  that  these  same 
limitations  of  religion  will  intensify  her  power.  This  is  well  illus- 
trated in  the  history  of  Israel,  Christianity  in  the  making,  for  the 
Hebrews  were  one  of  the  most  narrow-minded  nations,  intellectually, 
that  the  world  has  ever  seen :  they  could  not  be  compared  favorably 
with  the  Egyptians  for  mechanical  and  industrial  ability,  nor  with 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  INTELLECT  325 

the  Phoenicians  for  commerce,  nor  with  the  Philistines  for  art,  nor 
with  the  Assyrians  for  war,  nor  with  the  Babylonians  for  general 
versatility,  nor  with  the  Sumerians  for  literary  originality,  nor  with 
the  Greeks  for  philosophy,  nor,  we  may  add,  with  the  Anglo-Saxons 
for  science;  but,  nevertheless,  they  thought  the  more  profoundly  in 
religion  and  the  more  practically  in  morals.2  All  of  which  goes  to 
show  that  an  intensification  of  spiritual  experience  more  than  com- 
pensates for  a  want  of  general  inclusiveness. 

In  conclusion,  let  me  summarize  the  results  of  this  enquiry.  Some 
principle  of  differentiation  is  necessary  to  mark  the  proper  sphere 
of  religion  since  one  of  the  most  conspicious  signs  of  modern  religion 
is  the  breaking  up  of  the  traditional  religious  hegemony  that  has  so 
long  prevailed  over  all  departments  of  life.  Religion  also  must 
make  clear  her  distinctive  character  because  the  conditions  of  defi- 
nition require  a  positive  shrinking  in  extension  and  a  reduction  to 
more  precise  specification.  The  terms  in  which  religious  concepts 
are  expressed  may  be  the  changing  phases  of  life  of  successive  gener- 
ations, but  the  field  of  religious  interest  and  action  can  not  change. 
We  are  helped  in  marking  out  the  boundaries  of  this  permanent 
field  by  the  successful  tendency  for  specialization  conspicuous  to-day 
in  all  directions  and  approved  by  the  best  intelligence.  And  this, 
in  respect  to  religious  activities,  is  indubitably  the  field  of  moral 
interests  and  all  that  makes  for  righteousness  in  character  and  in 
nationality.  Here  lies  the  impregnable  stronghold  of  the  Kingdom. 
From  whatever  planes  of  activity  religious  forces  withdraw,  here 
the  retreat  must  ultimately  halt ;  and  within  these  specific  lines  re- 
ligion must  forever  exercise  her  control.  What  we  are  beginning, 
then,  to  see  is  this:  religion  not  only  subscribes  to  and  sanctions 
the  best  morality,  but  moral  character  itself  is  religion  objectified 
and  realized. 

H.  C.  ACKERMAN. 
NASHOTAH,  Wis. 

INTELLIGENCE  AND  INTELLECT 

IT  is  well  known  that  certain  words  and  terms  make  a  greater 
appeal  to  the  mind  of  the  public  than  others.  Psychologists  are 
perhaps  not  to  be  included  among  the  public,  inasmuch  as  they, 
in  common  with  all  other  scientists,  are  supposed  to  select  their  terms 
and  not  to  allow  themselves  to  be  guided  by  ordinary  usage.  But  try 
as  one  will,  there  are  certain  circumstances  which  rule  over  the  fate 

2(7/.  Laura  H.   Wild:    The   Evolution  of   tTie   Hebrew   People,   Part   IV 
passim. 


326  JO  URNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  words  and  so  bring  it  about  that  the  one  becomes  a  technical  term 
and  is  discussed  interminably  in  books  and  periodicals  while  the 
other,  with  just  as  high  a  pedigree,  is  relegated  to  the  plane  of  popu- 
lar parlance. 

Such  has  happened  with  the  two  words  "intelligence"  and  "in- 
tellect." Both  are  derived  from  a  common  source,  intelligere,  which, 
when  analyzed  into  its  components,  means  to  choose,  to  pick  out  (and 
incidentally  shows  what  good  psychological  insight  the  Romans  were 
possessed  of) ;  both  ran  almost  a  parallel  course  since  the  days  of  the 
Renaissance,  yet  of  the  two,  the  term  intelligence  had  the  more  event- 
ful career,  until  it  has  even  been  made  to  turn  a  behavioristic  somer- 
sault, while  intellect  is  still  the  staid  and  dignified  entity  as  of  old, 
and  as  a  result,  is  doomed  to  the  traditional  treatment  of  lexicog- 
raphers and  literary  men. 

From  the  very  first,  the  word  intelligence  had  the  advantage  in 
its  range  of  applicability.  The  distinction  drawn  between  intelli- 
gence and  intellect  in  the  Dictionary  of  Philosophy  and  Psychology 
is  not  clear-cut,  though  the  tendency  "to  apply  the  term  intellect 
more  especially  to  the  capacity  for  conceptual  thinking"  is  noted. 
The  delineation  of  the  same  term  in  the  Encyclopedia  Britannica  is 
carried  out  along  similar  lines.  "A  man  is  described  as  'intellectual* 
generally  because  he  is  occupied  with  theory  and  principles  rather 
than  with  practise,  often  with  the  further  implication  that  his  theories 
are  concerned  mainly  with  abstract  matters;  he  is  aloof  from  the 
world,  and  especially  is  a  man  of  training  and  culture  who  cares 
little  for  the  ordinary  pleasures  of  sense."  It  must  appear  evident 
to  most  readers  that  such  a  description  of  the  intellectual  man  does 
not  provide  us  with  the  cues  for  discriminating  between  intelligence 
and  intellect,  and  at  the  same  time  draws  a  too  sharp  antithesis 
between  two  qualities  which  may  subsist  in  the  same  individual.  Bis- 
marck, though  concerned  with  practical  matters  and  not  a  theoreti- 
cian, might  have  been  an  intellectual  person,  even  if  he  did  not  ac- 
tually happen  to  be  such.  Besides,  until  we  were  able  to  draw  the 
line  of  cleavage  between  the  theoretical  and  the  practical,  our  cri- 
terion would  be  of  no  avail.  The  same  observation  applies  to  the 
account  in  the  New  International  Encyclopedia  in  which  the  intel- 
lectual man  is  said,  according  to  current  usage,  to  possess  "special 
ability  in  dealing  with  the  abstract  and  theoretical,  while  the  intelli- 
gent man  is  efficient  in  concrete  situations  and  practical  affairs." 

In  his  article  on  "Animal  Intelligence"  in  the  Britannica,  Lloyd 
Morgan  sets  down  the  difference  as  one  between  perceptual  (sen- 
sory) and  conceptual  (ideational)  modes  of  behavior.  This  dis- 
tinction was  probably  grounded  in  the  results  obtained  in  animal  psy- 
chology, so  that  thanks  to  the  labors  of  Romanes,  the  phrase  "Animal 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  INTELLECT  327 

Intelligence"  became  one  of  the  most  widely  used  expressions  in 
psychology.  But  in  spite  of  its  empirical  background,  the  phrase 
pointed  to  a  particular  interpretation  which  need  not  necessarily  be 
accepted,  and  which,  furthermore,  was  vigorously  attacked  by  Was- 
mann  and  Mivart. 

Prof.  Warren  seems  to  think  that  the  term  intelligence,  as  applied 
to  animals  in  the  eighties  and  nineties,  had  acquired  a  distinctly  be- 
havioristie  meaning,  and  points  out  that  Thorndike,  in  particular, 
applied  it  to  his  mazes  and  trick  fastenings.  Commenting  on  my 
discussion  of  the  relation  between  intelligence  and  behavior,1  he 
writes  "I  have,  myself,  the  feeling  that  we  could  very  profitably 
revive  this  meaning  so  as  to  distinguish  between  intelligence  and 
intellect;  most  of  the  modern  mental  tests  are  really  intellect  tests, 
that  is,  tests  of  intellectual  intelligence  as  distinguished  from  the 
motor  or  skill  intelligence  tests  which  are  applied  to  animals."  It 
was  this  bit  of  comment  which  occasioned  the  writing  of  this  paper, 
especially  as  there  seems  to  be  an  ever-growing  need  of  a  criterion  to 
determine  which  is  intellect  and  which  is  intelligence,  the  more  so 
because  the  two  are  regarded  as  correlative  terms,  which  means  that 
what  we  hold  about  the  one  will  affect  our  view  of  the  other,  as  is 
evidenced  by  the  comparison  of  Lloyd  Morgan 's  and  "Warren 's  views. 
If  intellect  refers  to  the  conceptual,  intelligent  will  involve  the 
merely  perceptual ;  and,  if  we  take  it  that  intelligence  comprises  all 
performance  acts,  our  distinction  will  be  one  between  the  motor 
and  sensory  functions  of  man.  In  that  case  even  a  moron,  inso- 
much as  he  is  able  to  assimilate  knowledge,  may  be  regarded  as  pos- 
sessing intellect. 

Probably  every  educated  person  employs  the  two  words  in 
slightly  different  connections.  A  highly  cultured  person,  like  Car- 
lyle  or  Emerson  would,  in  all  likelihood,  not  feel  flattered  to  be  re- 
ferred to  as  very  intelligent.  To  the  man  in  the  street  such  a  recom- 
mendation would  no  doubt  appeal  as  an  acceptable  compliment.  In- 
telligence and  intellect  seem  to  be  made  of  the  same  texture,  but 
differ  in  their  degree  of  complexity.  This  distinction,  however,  is  not 
always  recognized  by  psychologists.  Thus,  Thorndike  in  his  Animal 
Intelligence  speaks  of  animal  intellect 2  as  evidently  an  interchange- 
able mode  of  expression  for  animal  intelligence,  while  most  intelli- 
gence testers,  as  Warren  observes,  are  really  occupying  themselves, 
to  a  considerable  extent,  with  the  problem  of  determining  the  intellect 
of  their  examinees.  Largely  with  this  consideration  in  view,  I  have 

iA.  A.  Roback,  "Intelligence  and  Behavior,"  Psychol.  Review,  1922, 
VoL  XXIX,  p.  54ff. 

2E.  L.  Thorndike,  Animal  Intelligence  (1911),  preface  p.  v.  and  Chapter 
VII. 


328  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

been  impelled  to  call  my  own  series  of  tests  for  superior  adults 
"mentality  tests,"  and  have  explained  elsewhere  my  reason  for  so 
doing,  viz.,  that  "intelligence"  has  been  used  to  "designate  a  much 
more  comprehensive  state  of  affairs.  Social  tact  and  savoir  faire, 
as  well  as  mechanical  ingenuity  and  motor  coordination,  are  all  sub- 
sumed under  the  general  category  of  intelligence.  It  is  obvious,  how- 
ever, that  what  we  can  concern  ourselves  with  here  is  at  most  the 
analysis  of  situations  that  are  distinctly  of  a  non-social  and  non- 
mechanical  sort. ' '  * 

The  distinction  between  intelligence  and  intellect  is  a  very  genu- 
ine one,  but  it  does  not  strike  me  that  the  essential  difference  lies  in 
the  fact  that  the  one  characterizes  motor  skill  or  even  mechanical  in- 
genuity and  the  other  applies  to  abstract  reasoning.  To  be  sure,  the 
term  animal  intelligence  was  in  vogue  among  animal  psychologists  for 
a  long  time  to  designate  the  capacity  for  motor  learning  in  infra- 
human  subjects,  but  in  all  such  cases  it  is  my  belief  that  the  aim  of 
the  investigators  was  to  prove  that  animals  possessed  mind,  that  they 
were  capable  of  understanding  situations.  Such  was  certainly  true 
of  Romanes  and  Wesley  Mills.  The  substitution  of  the  term  animal 
behavior  for  animal  intelligence  was  due  in  large  part  to  the  realiza- 
tion that  we  are  on  slippery  ground  whenever  the  question  of  inter- 
preting the  mental  state  of  an  animal  crops  up.  No  assumptions  are 
necessary — and  one  might  add  no  general  conclusions  are  forth- 
coming— on  the  basis  of  an  animal-behavior  psychology.  Another 
reason  for  the  shift  of  terms  is  probably  the  desire  to  break  down 
the  barrier  between  animal  psychology  and  biology  so  that  workers 
in  the  two  fields  might  carry  on  their  pursuits  on  common  ground. 
Thorndike  's  book  under  the  title  of  Animal  Intelligence,  which  came 
out  in  1911,  was,  it  will  be  remembered,  an  amplification  of  his 
monograph  published  in  1898,  when  the  term  behavior,  used  in  con- 
nection with  animal  reactions,  was  still  waiting  for  Jennings,  a  biolo- 
gist, to  give  it  currency.  Hence  the  somewhat  conservative  caption 
to  a  book  which  really  was  an  influential  factor  in  modifying  the 
older  views  about  animal  intelligence. 

The  distinction  then  between  intelligence  and  intellect  does  not 
appear  to  be  primarily  one  between  motor  capacity  and  the  power 
of  abstraction.  Intelligence  is  more  inclusive  than  intellect,  but,  at 
the  same  time,  it  is  marked  by  a  certain  desultoriness.  It  may  ap- 
pear in  detached  form.  This  view  does  not  necessarily  argue  for  the 
multimodality  of  intelligence.  An  individual  may  meet  with  success 
in  almost  everything  he  undertakes  to  do  and  yet  not  be  classed 

*"Beport  on  the  Roback  Mentality  Tests  at  Simmons  College,"  Simmons 
College  Review,  1921,  Vol.  HI,  p.  314. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  INTELLECT  329 

with  the  intellectual.  What  is  it  then  that  gives  one  the  stamp  of  in- 
tellect? It  is,  to  my  mind,  the  concatenation  of  the  most  essential 
intelligences  into  a  systematic  whole — most  essential  for  that  pur- 
pose, of  course — that  constitutes  the  distinguishing  feature  of  intel- 
lect. This  quality  must  not  be  confused  with  what  has  been  called 
creative  intelligence,  for  a  great  artist  or  a  great  inventor  is  not  nec- 
essarily a  man  of  great  intellect,  nor  must  the  distinction  be  viewed, 
in  the  light  of  Stern's  proper  dichotomy  between  genius  and  intel- 
ligence.4 That  mental  integrity  constitutes  a  prime  condition  of  in- 
tellect is,  to  a  large  extent,  recognized  in  popular  parlance  when  we 
speak  of  Aristotle  being  a  great  intellect,  though  an  ordinary  man 
is  said  to  possess  intelligence.  This  usage  is  not  a  mere  synecdoche, 
but  represents  the  deep-rooted  conviction  of  educated  people  which 
experience  has  taught  them.  Csesar  was  probably  more  intelligent 
than  Marcus  Aurelius,  but  Marcus  Aurelius  was  the  greater  intellect. 
A  man  may  get  along  with  people,  who  nevertheless  is  unable  to 
understand  them  or  appraise  their  merits  and  faults.  Another  may 
not  be  so  successful  in  his  dealings  with  the  world  and  yet  have 
a  keen  insight  into  affairs.  The  latter  is  the  more  intellectual.  It 
is  he  who  not  only  grasps  a  situation,  though  not  necessarily  every 
situation,  but  is  also  able  to  relate  his  experiences  and  observations 
to  one  another  so  as  to  build  up  a  Weltanschauung  (which  need  not 
be  a  system  of  philosophy) .  Paradoxical  as  the  statement  may  sound, 
it  is  my  belief  that  there  are  cases  when  one  knows  how  things  are 
done  without  being  able  to  do  them  himself.  An  intellectual  man, 
then,  will  not  always  be  thought  intelligent  in  the  accepted  sense  of 
the  word,  for  his  capacity  will  not  comprise  possibly  the  wide  range 
of  activities  covered  by  intelligence,  but  by  way  of  compensation, 
he  has  a  great  deal  more  to  show  in  the  upper  levels  of  the  narrower 
range — upper  because  the  activities  in  that  region  presuppose  a 
knowledge  of  the  more  common  activities.  The  intelligent  man  lives 
in  a  shed  extending  over  a  vast  area ;  the  man  of  intellect  dwells  in 
a  sky-scraper,  communicating  with  every  nook  and  corner  of  the 
building  and  aware  of  every  happening  in  his  abode  and  its  bearing 
upon  every  other  happening. 

In  short,  the  secret  of  intellect  is  coordination  on  a  large  scale. 
Naturally,  the  experiences  requisite  for  such  an  activity  must  be 
plentiful,  comprising  not  only  one's  own  but  those  of  many  others. 
For  this  reason  erudition  has  been  considered  the  basis  of  intellect, 
and  rightly  so.  The  perfect  type  of  coordination  would  involve 
an  acquaintance  with  all  the  facts  in  every  conceivable  department 
of  knowledge.  The  more  data  we  have  at  our  command  in  the  most 

*  "W.  Stern,  Psycliological  Methods  of  Testing  Intelligence,  p.  4. 


330  JO  URNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

diverse  fields  of  human  endeavor,  covering  the  greatest  period  of 
time,  the  more  we  approximate  this  ideal.  It  does  not  follow  that 
the  professional  philosopher  is  the  man  of  intellect  par  excellence, 
though  his  particular  studies  must  surely  provide  him  with  the  best 
opportunity  for  such  attainment.  Herder,  Schopenhauer,  Carlyle, 
and  Renan,  disparate  as  they  all  are  from  one  another,  seem  to  typify 
the  intellectual  in  modern  times.  In  general  one  may  say  that  the 
romanticists  have  the  advantage  over  the  classicists  in  this  regard  be- 
cause their  scope  extends  over  greater  dimensions.  The  quality  of 
the  coordination  is  probably  superior  in  the  latter,  but  as  has  al- 
ready been  intimated,  no  matter  how  careful  we  are  with  our  selec- 
tion, if  the  wherewithals  are  not  within  our  reach,  the  choice  of 
the  materials  can  not  but  be  faulty. 

The  statement  has  been  made  above,  and  it  accords  with  the  re- 
ceived view,  that  intelligence  is  a  more  comprehensive  term  than 
intellect.  But  the  subsequent  discussion  goes  to  show  that  this  com- 
prehensiveness relates  to  the  situations  to  be  met  with  by  the  individ- 
ual. Now  a  great  many  of  these  situations  are  not  taken  into  account 
in  the  adjudication  of  intellect,  but  vastly  more  is  included  instead, 
to  wit,  the  experience  of  the  race  and  its  outstanding  figures.  The 
man  of  intellect  is  not  called  upon  to  settle  a  strike,  to  repair  a  lock, 
to  act  the  affable  host  and  the  like ;  his  task  is  much  more  enormous, 
for  he  deals  with  a  vast  body  of  complicated  facts  which  he  must 
sift  and  colligate  and  reflect  on. 

After  setting  down  the  criterion  of  intellect  and  intelligence,  we 
have  still  to  consider  the  constitutional  difference  between  the  two. 
In  the  man  of  intellect  there  appears  to  be  an  urge  towards  systemati- 
zation  which,  if  not  lacking,  is  at  any  rate  not  pronounced  in  the  in- 
telligent person,  who,  to  be  sure,  may  evince  an  ambitious  spirit,  may 
even  direct  all  his  energies  towards  becoming  a  leader.  In  such  an  in- 
dividual the  "drive"  towards  his  goal  may  be  actually  consummated, 
but  often  the  means  employed,  the  very  skill  exercised,  betrays  the 
want  of  mental  integrity  which  is  a  proprium  of  intellect.  The  fact 
that  single-mindedness  was  not  always  a  characteristic  of  intellectual 
men — Voltaire,  for  instance — should  not  invalidate  my  thesis.  As  in 
everything  else,  deviations  from  a  standard  are  to  be  measured  in 
relation  to  the  components  which  go  to  make  up  the  criterion  and 
treated,  moreover,  on  a  comparative  basis.  The  flaw  in  Voltaire's 
character  must  indubitably  have  affected  not  only  his  results  but  his 
coordinating  ability  as  well. 

A.  A.  ROBACK. 

HARVARD  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  331 

BOOK  EEVIEWS 

The  Works  of  Aristotle  Translated  into  English,  Vol.  X.,  Politica, 

Oeconomica,    Atheniensum    Respublica.      Oxford:     Clarendon 

Press,  1921. 

This  tenth  volume  of  the  great  Oxford  translation  of  Aristotle, 
edited  by  W.  D.  Ross,  must  be  welcomed  by  all  students  of  Aristotle 
and  should  be  welcomed  by  all  students  of  politics.  The  re-issuing 
of  the  Jowett  translation  of  the  Politics  is  explained  by  the  editor 
as  follows.  "Piety  towards  Dr.  Jowett,  whose  munificence  has 
made  possible  the  production  of  this  translation  of  Aristotle,  sug- 
gested that  no  new  rendering  of  the  Politics  should  be  attempted." 
Certainly  no  other  English  translation  reads  so  well  as  Jowett 's, 
but  unfortunately  the  reader  should  be  conscious  that  he  is  fre- 
quently reading  Jowett  and  not  Aristotle.  I  give  one  illustration 
of  the  liberties  which  Jowett  took.  The  lines  1258  b,  8-11,  trans- 
lated literally,  read  about  as  follows:  "We  have  discussed  suffi- 
ciently the  science  of  the  subject  (business  or  finance),  and  ought 
now  to  discuss  its  practise.  In  all  such  matters  freedom  reigns  in 
understanding  them,  but  necessity  in  practising  them."  In  Jow- 
ett 's  translation  they  read :  ' '  Enough  has  been  said  about  the  theory 
of  wealth-getting;  we  will  now  proceed  to  the  practical  part.  The 
discussion  of  such  matters  is  not  unworthy  of  philosophy,  but  to  be 
engaged  in  them  practically  is  illiberal  and  irksome."  The  editor, 
in  this  case,  has  given  in  a  footnote  Bernays'  translation:  "We 
are  free  to  speculate  about  them,  but  in  practise  we  are  limited  by 
circumstances."  This  method  of  calling  attention  to  improve- 
ments in  translation  or  to  more  recent  scholarship  on  the  texts  is 
followed  throughout  and  is  valuable.  But  the  revision  of  the  Jow- 
ett translation  thus  effected  is  still  quite  inadequate.  The  Welldon 
translation  is  superior  in  point  of  accuracy,  but  it  too  leaves  much 
to  be  desired.  For  instance,  in  Welldon  the  above  passage  reads: 
"Having  now  sufficiently  discussed  the  theory  of  Finance,  we  have 
next  to  describe  its  practical  application.  It  is  to  be  observed  how- 
ever that  in  all  such  matters  speculation  is  free,  while  in  practise 
there  are  limiting  conditions."  Welldon  here  corrects  Jowett 's 
error,  but  he  introduces  an  error  of  his  own  in  the  first  part  of  the 
passage.  There  is  still  needed  an  English  translation  to  equal  the 
French  of  St.  Hilaire,  which  has  the  merits  of  both  accuracy  and 
a  fluent  style. 

E.  S.  Foster's  translation  of  the  Economics  is  a  great  improve- 
ment over  the  old  Walford  translation  in  the  Bohn  Series,  and 
makes  the  treatise  very  attractive  reading.  It  deserves  to  be  much 
more  generally  known  than  it  is.  The  first  book  is  generally  re- 


332  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

garded,  following  Zeller,  as  not  genuine,  although  on  rather  slight 
evidence.  It  is  an  excellent  illustration  of  the  "common-sense" 
character  of  Aristotle's  philosophy,  consisting  of  observations  on 
how  households  are  successfully  conducted,  observations  so  com- 
monplace as  to  escape  being  written  except  by  Aristotle  or  in  prov- 
erbs. One  is  interested  to  read  in  Aristotle,  for  example,  that 
"there  are  occasions  when  a  master  should  rise  while  it  is  still 
night;  for  this  helps  to  make  a  man  healthy  and  wealthy  and  wise." 
The  second  book  of  the  Economics  is  obviously  post-Aristotelian, 
and  consists  of  a  collection  of  most  entertaining  anecdotes  about 
royal,  satrapic,  political  and  personal  economy. 

Sir  Frederic  G.  Kenyon's  latest  revision  of  his  excellent  trans- 
lation of  the  Athenian  Constitution  needs  no  further  comment,  as 
his  work  both  as  a  translator  and  as  an  editor  of  the  texts,  is  well 
known. 

The  addition  of  copious  footnotes  and  the  careful  indexing  of 
the  books  make  this  edition  of  Aristotle  all  the  more  attractive. 

H.  W.  SCHNEIDER. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

Etude  sur  le  Terme  ATNAMI2  dans  les   Dialogues   de  Platon. 

JOSEPH  SOUILHE.    Paris,  1919. 

The  aim  of  this  modest  and  thorough  piece  of  work  is,  first,  to 
help  make  precise  the  Platonic  vocabulary  and  thus  the  Platonic 
philosophy;  second,  to  prepare  a  more  complete  knowledge  of  the 
Aristotelian  theory  of  potentiality  (p.  xi).  To  achieve  this  aim 
M.  Souilhe"  follows  the  models  of  Hitter's  "  EISo?  I8«fo  und  ver- 
wandte  Woerte  in  den  Schriften  Platons"  published  in  his  Neue 
Untersuchungen  ueber  Platon  and  of  A.  E.  Taylor's  "The  words 
e'So<?,  tS^a  in  pre-Platonic  literature"  from  the  Varia  Socratica. 

Probably  no  model  could  be  better  for  this  sort  of  work  than 
Mr.  Taylor's,  especially  if  one  is  equipped  with  as  sure  a  lexico- 
graphical sense  as  his.  For  it  emphasizes  the  actual  use  of  the 
words  in  question  and  not  what  people  say  the  use  is.  Thus  by 
actual  comparison  and  analysis  one  obtains  not  a  mere  unsubstan- 
tial guess  at  what  the  Greeks  may  have  been  talking  about,  but  a 
careful  determination  made  inductively  with  the  evidence  plainly 
exhibited.  Plato,  in  this  case,  is  put  in  a  Greek  setting  among  his 
fellow  thinkers.  To  study  him  thus  is  surely  to  run  less  risk  of 
modernizing  him,  if  nothing  else,  and  that  is  of  course  one  of  the 
easiest  mistakes  to  make  in  interpreting  the  ancients.  The  result 
incidentally  throws  light  on  the  whole  workings  of  the  Greek  scien- 
tific mind,  a  field  which  lies  outside  M.  Souilhe's  immediate  inter- 
ests, unfortunately. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  333 

The  study  begins  with  a  resume  of  the  primitive  use  of  the  word 
and  its  derivatives.  The  texts  here  are  taken  from  belles 
lettres,  from  Homer  to  Demosthenes.  It  is  found  that  it  has  four 
senses:  first,  the  primitive  notion  of  physical  force  which  de- 
velops to  any  kind  of  superiority;  second,  the  power  of  inanimate 
things,  money,  sickness,  law;  third,  by  transferences  to  the  things 
which  have  the  power  and  superiority,  armies,  governments,  for- 
tunes; fourth,  reducing  the  idea  of  value,  simple  ability,  posse  not 
potentia. 

The  use  of  a  word  in  belles  lettres  is  usually  more  indicative  of 
its  connotation  than  its  denotation.  One  would  look  in  vain  today 
for  the  meaning  of  Royce's  "loyalty,"  Dewey's  "situation,"  San- 
tayana's  "essence,"  Watson's  "behavior"  in  the  speeches  of  Con- 
gressmen, the  poetry  of  the  Imagists,  or  the  dramas  of  Mr.  Shaw. 
But  one  might  find  there  a  certain  haze  of  suggestiveness  which  might 
be  of  interest.  So  in  M.  Souilhe's  study  these  passages  are  utilized 
as  a  simple  background  against  which  are  thrown  the  words  as  used 
by  the  mathematicians,  the  physicians,  and  the  sophists. 

Aui>a/u?  in  mathematics  is  found  to  mean  "fundamental  or  dis- 
tinctive property."  Thus  the  tetrade  is  called  the  Svvafus  of  the 
decade  because  the  equilateral  triangle  which  is  used  to  represent 
ten,  the  tetraktys,1  is  that  from  which  the  decade  is  developed.  This 
is  a  technical  application  of  the  popular  meaning  "superiority." 
For,  as  in  Aristotle,  that  which  produces  is  superior  to  that  which  is 
produced.  Similarly  the  square  of  a  number  is  the  second  power 
(Suz/o/LM?),  which  looks  as  if  the  mathematicians  had  an  eye  for  the 
generative  functions  in  the  operations  of  their  science  (p.  29). 

An  analogous  use  of  words  is  observable  in  the  treatises  on 
medicine  (p.  36).  There  substances  are  held  to  manifest  themselves 
by  their  qualities,  hot,  cold,  bitter,  salty,  and  the  like.  But  the 
cold  differs  from  the  hot,  the  moist  from  the  dry,  in  the  effects  they 
produce.  Both  the  power  substances  have  to  make  themselves  mani- 
fest and  the  power  they  have  to  act  in  characteristic  ways  are 
Svvdneis.  The  body  of  texts  cited  by  M.  Souilhie  from  the  physi- 
cians shows  how  the  term  we  have  grown  to  look  upon  as  almost 
exclusively  Aristotelian  was  in  reality  one  of  the  scientific  terms 
of  his  contemporaries.  "In  the  treatises  of  the  Hippocratic  Collec- 
tion," says  M.  Souilhe,  "in  those  above  all  wherein  the  influence 
of  the  cosmological  ideas  of  the  first  physicians2  is  particularly  evi- 
dent, the  term  Svvajjus  designates  the  characteristic  property  of 
bodies,  the  external  and  sensory  side,  that  which  permits  us  to 

1  V.  Bui-net's  Early  Greek  Philosophy,  3d  ed.,  p.  102. 

2  In  the  Greek  sense  of  the  word  I  suppose. 


334          JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


determine  and  specify  them.  Thanks  to  the  Swap?,  the  mysteri- 
ous <f>v<ri<;t  the  substantial  eZSo?  or  primordial  element,  makes  itself 
known,  and  makes  itself  known  by  its  action.  Starting  from  this 
point  we  understand  .  .  .  how  easy  it  was  to  establish  a  perfect 
equation  between  <f>v<ri<i  and  Sin/a/**?"  (p.  55f.).  The  same  use  of 
the  word  is  found  in  the  fragments  of  Gorgias  and  Isocrates. 

In  Plato  the  word  has  more  philosophic  importance  than  else- 
where, but  here  too  it  means  that  quality  which  beings  have  to  re- 
veal to  us  their  peculiar  constitution,  shown  in  action  or  in  being 
acted  upon  (p.  149).  This  is  the  same  as  the  Hippocratic  use  of 
the  term.  But  M.  Souilh£  does  not  agree  with  Hitter  that  Plato 
equates  Swapis  and  ovaia  (p.  156).  Small  though  the  detail  may 
be,  it  is  what  determines  in  large  measure  whether  Plato's  universe 
is  to  be  interpreted  as  a  process  or  as  something  static.  If  one  'a 
imagination  is  allowed  to  play  on  the  various  consequences,  one 
will  see  the  importance  of  knowing  just  what  Plato  did  mean,  if 
that  be  a  possibility. 

It  seems  a  greater  possibility  now  that  we  have  studies  of  Plato  's 
vocabulary  which  are  being  done  by  scholars  with  sufficient  equip- 
ment for  the  task.  The  study  of  M.  Souilhe  may  be  open  to  un- 
favorable criticism  in  detail,  but  one  would  have  to  be  very  fussy 
to  accord  it  anything  but  praise  as  a  whole.  He  seems  to  have  ap- 
proached the  problem  with  as  few  preconceived  ideas  as  possible 
and  to  have  spared  no  pains  to  investigate  it  with  all  thoroughness. 
One  could  legitimately  hope  for  a  more  extended  discussion  of  the 
results,  particularly  of  their  effect  upon  the  interpretation,  of 
Plato's  philosophy  as  a  whole.  That  may  of  course  be  too  much  to 
ask  of  a  study  which  has  purposely  limited  itself  to  a  special  phase 
of  a  problem.  It  does  not  seem  likely,  however,  that  students  of 
Plato  can  afford  to  neglect  this  work,  certainly  not  university  stu- 
dents. 

GEORGE  BOAS. 

THE  JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

SCIENTIA.  November,  1921.  Euclidean  Constructions  (pp. 
345-354) :  H.  P.  HUDSON  (Croydon,  England). — Illustrations  of  how 
algebraic  analysis  can  reveal  what  can  and  what  can  not  be  done  with 
ruler  and  compass.  L'origine  de  la  chaleur  solaire  (pp.  355-370) : 
JEAN  PERRIN  (Paris). — Admirable  exposition  of  the  interesting  hy- 
pothesis that  in  the  process  of  forming  heavier  and  heavier  atoms 
the  mass  of  the  sun  is  diminished,  being  partly  converted  into  energy. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  335 

This  energy  would  suffice  to  keep  up  the  present  solar  radiation  for 
several  trillion  years.  Radioactivity  is  a  secondary  reverse  process 
of  minor  importance.  A  paper  decidedly  worth  consulting.  Le  milieu 
geographique  et  la  race  (pp.  371-380) :  A.  A.  MENDES-CORREA 
(Porto). — Suggests  the  difficulty  of  proving  specific  cases  of  influence 
exercised  on  racial  characters  by  geographic  environment,  yet  con- 
cludes that  environment  must,  nevertheless,  be  an  important  factor. 
Buts  et  resultats  coloniaux  de  la  guerre  mondiale.  II.  Les  resultats 
economico-juridiques  (pp.  381-392)  :  G.  MONDAINI  (Borne). — Empha- 
sizes the  reactionary  character  of  many  of  the  recent  legal  changes 
in  the  status  of  colonies  throughout  the  world  and  especially  in  the 
Congo.  L'auvremathematique  de  Klein  (pp.  393-396)  :  F.  ENRIQUES 
(Bologna). — A  characterization  of  Klein's  work  in  synthetic  geome- 
try, with  reference  to  his  preparing  the  way  for  Einstein.  Reviews 
of  Scientific  Books  and  Periodicals. 

Baez,  C.  Eangel.    Nuevas  Orientaciones  Cientificas.    Caracas,  Vene- 
zuela :  Tipografia  Vargas.    1922.    Pp.56. 
Gentile,  Giovanni.    The  Theory  of  Mind  as  Pure  Act.    Translated 

from  the  third  edition,  with  an  introduction  by  H.  Wildon  Carr. 

London :  Macmillan  &  Co.    1922.    Pp.  xxvii  -f  277. 
Gilson,  Etienne.     La  Philosophic  au  Moyen  Age.     Two  volumes. 

Paris:  Payot  &  Cie.    1922.    Pp.  160,  159. 
Hall,  Stanley.    Senescence :  The  Last  Half  of  Life.    New  York :  D. 

Appleton  &  Co.    1922.    Pp.  xxvii  -f  518. 

Lalo,  Charles.    Aristote.    Paris:  Paul  Mellottee.    Pp.  159.    2.50  fr. 
Lalo,  Charles.    L 'Art  et  la  Morale.    Paris :  Felix  Alcan.    1922.    Pp. 

184.    7  fr. 
Rogers,  Arthur  Kenyon.     English  and  American  Philosophy  since 

1800.    New  York :  Macmillan  Co.    1922.    Pp.  xiv  +  468. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 
AMERICAN  PHILOSOPHICAL  ASSOCIATION:  WESTERN  DIVISION 

It  will  interest  the  members  who  could  not  be  present  at  the 
Lincoln  Meeting,  April  14th  and  15th,  to  know  that  in  addition  to 
holding  the  announced  programme,  ten  names  were  added  to  the 
roster  of  the  Western  Division,  and  the  following  actions  were 
taken:  (1)  that  it  is  the  wish  of  the  Western  Division  that  the  first 
Joint  Meeting  of  the  two  divisions  be  held  next  December,  in  ac- 
cordance with  the  expressed  wish  of  the  Eastern  Division,  and  that, 
if  it  be  agreeable  to  the  Eastern  Division,  it  be  held  either  in  New 
York  City  or  vicinity;  (2)  that  the  December  joint  meeting  of 


336  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

1922  take  the  place  of  the  Easter  Meeting  in  1923,  subject  to  the  ap- 
proval of  the  officers-elect. 

It  will  be  remembered  that  a  year  ago,  at  the  Chicago  Meeting, 
the  Western  Division  proposed — and  the  Eastern  Division  at  its  last 
December  Meeting  concurred  in  the  proposal — that  the  first  Joint 
Meeting  of  the  two  divisions  should  be  made  the  occasion  of  the  de- 
livery by  John  Dewey  of  the  Paul  Carus  Lectures.  At  Lincoln  the 
question  was  raised  whether  there  should  be  the  usual  programme 
in  addition  to  the  Paul  Carus  Lectures,  which  might  possibly  occur 
on  Wednesday,  Thursday  and  Friday  of  Christmas  week.  The  gen- 
eral opinion  was  that  there  should  be  such  a  programme,  and  it  was 
left  to  the  two  executive  committees  to  decide  whether  it  be  a  joint 
programme,  or  two  entirely  independent  programmes,  or  two  pro- 
grammes with  alternating  sessions  so  that  all  could  attend  both. 
Further  notice  will  be  sent  as  soon  as  the  plan  is  worked  out. 

Will  the  members  of  the  Western  Division  permit  the  Secretary 
to  mention  the  importance  of  making  this  first  Joint  Meeting  a  com- 
plete and,  if  possible,  enthusiastic  success?  The  idea  suggested  by 
Mrs.  Mary  Hegeler  Carus 's  gift  of  a  thousand  dollars  for  the  com- 
ing series  of  Paul  Cams  Lectures,  viz.,  the  idea  that  it  would  be 
desirable,  if  possible,  to  establish  such  an  American  Lectureship  in 
Philosophy  on  a  permanent  foundation,  is  in  mind  as  we  write ;  an 
enthusiastic  appreciation  of  this  idea,  shown  by  a  large  attendance 
and  a  cordial  spirit  at  this  first  meeting,  might  help  much  toward 
that  very  desirable  end. 

The  executive  committee  elected  for  1922-23  are:  President, 
E.  L.  Schaub;  Vice-President,  R.  W.  Sellars;  Secretary-Treasurer, 
G.  A.  Tawney;  E.  D.  Starbuck,  L.  P.  Brogan,  A.  W.  Moore  and 
Rupert  C.  Lodge.  It  is  hoped  that  reprints  of  the  Lincoln  address 
of  President  E.  S.  Ames  on  "Religious  Values"  will  be  ready  for 
distribution  soon.  It  will  include  a  revised  list  of  members. 

Professor  Dewey  has  not  yet  named  the  topic  of  his  Paul  Cams 
Lectures,  but  he  intimates  that  they  will  be  a  study  of  the  various 
critical  approaches  to  Instrumentalism  with  a  view  to  clarifying 
the  issues  it  raises.  It  is  sure  to  be  of  immense  interest. 

G.  A.  TAWNEY. 
UNIVERSITY  or  CINCINNATI. 

Professor  Pick,  the  well-known  neurologist  at  Prague,  is  about 
to  retire  from  teaching  and  wants  to  sell  his  library.  It  contains 
some  3,000  works  on  psychiatry,  neurology  and  psychology  in  Eng- 
lish, French  and  German,  besides  7,000  reprints  and  theses.  The 
price  is  $4,000.  Address  Professor  Arnold  Pick,  Jungmannstrasse, 
26.,  Prague,  Czechoslovakia. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  13  JUNE  22,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  NEW  MATERIALISM 

ONE  of  the  most  characteristic  phenomena  of  the  very  disinte- 
grated thought  of  our  time  is  the  recrudescence  of  material- 
ism. From  Biichner's  or  at  any  rate  from  Tyndal's  day  to  the  end 
of  the  nineteenth  century  materialism  had  suffered  a  fairly  steady 
loss  in  the  confidence  of  the  thinking  world,  so  that  twenty  years 
ago  it  seemed  almost  a  dead  issue  in  philosophy.  Ernst  Haeckel 
was  indeed  still  faithful  to  the  lost  cause;  but  even  he,  before  his 
death,  gave  it  up  in  all  its  more  extreme  forms  and  went  over  to  the 
' '  double  aspect  theory. ' ' 1  But  the  sick  man  of  philosophy,  as 
materialism  might  have  been  called  a  few  years  ago,  has  quite 
recently  taken  on  a  new  lease  of  life  and  has  found  a  new  circle  of 
able  defenders. 

The  reason  for  the  steady  loss  of  credence  which  materialism 
suffered  toward  the  close  of  the  last  century  was,  as  I  think  will  be 
generally  acknowledged,  not  lack  of  interest  in  it  nor  any  peculiar- 
ity of  the  psychological  atmosphere  of  the  times  nor  a  change  in  in- 
tellectual taste,  but  just  certain  very  definite  logical  considerations. 
The  materialistic  doctrine  had  never  been  perfectly  clear  of  itself 
but  wobbled  between  two  forms,  both  of  which  had  their  very  great 
logical  difficulties.  One  form  of  materialism  identified  conscious- 
ness with  matter  or  with  brain  energy,  especially  with  motion;  the 
other  asserted  that  consciousness,  while  not  identical  with  the  brain 
or  its  activities,  was  always  the  result  of  these  activities  and  never 
itself  a  determinant  either  of  action  or  even  of  the  later  stages  of 
its  own  series.  Now  as  the  nineteenth  century  grew  older,  the  dif- 
ficulties involved  in  both  these  doctrines  became  clearer  until  they 
seemed  at  last  quite  fatal.  The  fir^t  formulation  of  materialism  in- 
deed left  consciousness  efficient,  but  did  so  only  by  an  identification 
which  was  clearly  seen  to  be  nonsense  if  such  a  thing  as  nonsense 
can  be.  We  know  what  we  mean  by  pains  and  pleasures,  by 
thoughts  and  purposes  and  desires;  we  know  also,  in  a  general  way 
at  least,  what  we  mean  by  brain  cells  and  their  real  and  possible 
motions;  and  if  we  do  not  and  can  not  know  that  these  are  differ- 
ent it  is  hopeless  that  we  should  ever  know  anything.  The  diffi- 
culties involved  in  the  second  formulation  of  materialism  are  peiv 

i  Cf.  his  Gott-Natur,  Leipzig,  1914. 

337 


338  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

haps  not  so  obvious,  but  to  nearly  all  thinkers  of  twenty  years 
ago  they  seemed  none  the  less  fatal.  These  difficulties  cropped 
out  in  many  forms,  but  all  the  more  important  ones  were  varia- 
tions of  the  denial  of  efficiency  to  consciousness.  For  example,  how 
shall  the  materialist  explain  the  development  of  consciousness,  hav- 
ing denied  to  it  any  influence  upon  the  activities  of  the  organism? 
James's  formulation  of  this  question  in  his  famous  chapter  on  the 
Automaton  Theory  has  never  been  satisfactorily  answered  and 
seemed  in  itself  very  nearly  decisive.  Equally  ominous  for  ma- 
terialism was  the  bearing  of  the  asserted  inefficiency  of  conscious- 
ness on  human  reasoning  processes.  For  materialism  maintains 
(as  obviously  it  must)  that  each  thought  is  determined  wholly  by 
the  preceding  or  accompanying  brain  states  and  not  at  all  by  the 
preceding  thoughts.  This  being  the  case,  what  we  commonly  refer 
to  as  reasoned  conclusions  turn  out  not  to  be  reasoned  at  all  but 
simply  caused  by  the  entirely  non-logical  mechanical  laws  of  brain 
activity.  There  can  not,  therefore,  be  any  such  thing  as  logical 
necessity  in  any  of  our  reasoning  processes.  The  perception  of 
logical  relations  has  nothing  to  do  with  them,  nor  has  even  the 
recognition  of  rational  probability;  they  are  determined  solely  by 
mechanical  necessity.  The  materialist  is  plainly  bound  to  maintain 
this.  He  is  still  bound  to  maintain  it  when  asked  how  he  knows 
his  theory  is  true.  To  this  question  he  can  not  reply  that  material- 
ism is  the  logically  necessary  nor  even  the  reasonably  probable  de- 
duction from  the  facts,  for  the  perception  of  logical  connections 
has  nothing  to  do  with  guiding  man's  conscious  processes.  All  he 
can  say  is  that  the  mechanical  processes  of  his  brain  make  him 
think  as  he  does,  but  that  as  for  proving  the  truth  of  his  or  of  any 
other  theory,  that  is  a  thing  impossible  for  man. 

Many  other  considerations  of  this  sort  might  be  pressed  with 
cumulative  effect,  as  was  realized  by  our  predecessors ;  and  to  them 
they  appeared  decisive.  In  short  the  assertion  to  which  material- 
ism is  necessarily  committed  that  all  the  purposeful  and  intelligent 
activities  of  the  individual,  the  construction  of  civilization,  of  hu- 
man literature,  philosophy  and  science,  the  entire  evolution  of  con- 
scious beings,  have  been  utterly  unaffected  by  consciousness  and  are 
merely  the  result  of  the  laws  of  matter — this  assertion,  once  it  was 
fully  grasped,  seemed  too  preposterous  for  serious  consideration. 
Other  theories  of  mind  and  body  might  have  their  difficulties;  but 
greater  difficulties  than  these  were  hardly  conceivable. 

One  further  reason  for  the  nineteenth  century's  definite  rejec- 
tion of  materialism  was  to  be  found  in  the  fact  that  the  great  motive 
which  had  led  to  the  popularizing  of  this  doctrine, — namely  the  de- 


THE  NEW  MATERIALISM  339 

sire  to  give  naturalism  full  sway  through  all  the  world  of  matter 
and  energy — was  fully  shared  by  parallelism;  that  parallelism,  in 
fact,  was  even  more  favorable  to  naturalism  than  was  materialism 
(in  its  second  formulation),  inasmuch  as  it  retained  the  theory  of 
the  conservation  of  energy  quite  intact.  For  these  reasons  the 
great  majority  of  the  adherents  of  naturalism  went  over  from  ma- 
terialism to  parallelism.  Toward  the  close  of  the  century  both 
materialism  and  interaction  seemed  to  be  definitively  abandoned, 
and  parallelism  remained  almost  without  rival  in  possession  of  the 
field. 

If  the  rise  of  parallelism  in  the  last  half  of  the  nineteenth  cen- 
tury was  in  part  the  cause  of  the  decline  of  materialism,  the  pres- 
ent recrudescence  of  materialism  is  due  in  no  small  degree  to  the 
notable  decline  in  the  popularity  of  parallelism.  The  fickleness  of 
Fortune  has  seldom  been  more  tragically  illustrated  than  in  the 
slump  suffered  by  parallelism  in  the  last  few  years.  The  causes  of 
this  slump  are  to  be  found  in  the  fact  that  once  fully  understood 
parallelism  is  seen  to  have  logical  difficulties  of  its  own  so  serious  as 
to  be  fatal ;  but  our  interest  in  parallelism  for  the  present  is  confined 
to  the  effect  which  its  decline  has  had  in  initiating  a  revival  of  ma- 
terialism. For  the  naturalistic  philosophers  who  could  not  feel 
comfortable  in  the  parallelist  camp  are  now  trooping  back  to  their 
old  haunts  and  reviving  their  ancient  loyalty.  Most  of  them,  to  be 
sure,  are  not  as  yet  under  the  old  flag  nor  do  they  use  the  old  de- 
signation; the  majority  call  themselves  behaviorists  or  neo-realists 
or  pragmatists — or  idealists.  There  are  a  few,  however,  who  are 
frank  enough  to  hoist  the  old  ensign  and  attempt  a  serious  resus- 
citation of  materialism  as  such.  Among  the  leaders  of  this  move- 
ment I  shall  mention  only  Professors  Warren,  Montague,  and  Sel- 
lars.  Professor  Strong  should  certainly  be  added  to  this  list — 
provided  one  could  be  sure  that  he  is  really  a  materialist  and  not 
still  in  some  sense  a  parallelist.  If  he  belongs  in  the  former  cate- 
gory his  materialism  rests  upon  an  identification  of  psychic  states 
with  material  particles.  This,  so  far  as  it  goes,  would  of  course  be 
open  to  the  same  objections  as  the  first  form  of  the  old  materialism. 
Professor  Strong  seems  at  times  to  accept  this  identification  and 
to  seek  to  make  it  more  thinkable  by  distinguishing  between  the 
psychical  and  the  conscious.  In  addition  to  this  distinction  one 
must  keep  in  mind  Professor  Strong's  fundamental  doctrine  that 
introspection  is  always  indirect  and  of  the  past.  If  one  puts  these 
considerations  together  it  follows  that  we  are  never  directly  con- 
scious of  our  psychic  states  and  hence  that  they  may,  for  aught  we 
know,  be  identical  with  the  brain.  Yet  I  can  not  see  that  this 


340  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

really  avoids  the  old  difficulty;  for  if  psychic  states  are  really 
psychic  it  is  hard  to  put  any  meaning  into  the  assertion  that  they 
are  brain ;  and  if  they  are  not  really  psychic  the  cognizing  of  them 
must  be,  and  the  old  difficulty  will  break  out  in  a  new  place.  Fur- 
thermore, it  is  exceedingly  difficult  for  me,  at  least,  to  see  how 
panpsychism  (to  which  Professor  Strong  still  clings)  is  to  be  made 
consistent  with  his  critical  realism,  or  to  understand  how  a  psychic 
state  can  be  extended  and  possess  really  (not  as  mere  appearance) 
the  various  primary  qualities.  If  it  is  by  considerations  such  as 
these  that  the  ills  of  materialism  are  to  be  cured  I  fear  the  cure 
will  prove  worse  than  the  disease.  However,  I  am  not  at  all  sure 
that  Professor  Strong  means  this  for  materialism,  for,  as  I  have 
said,  he  still  clings  (with  modifications)  to  the  panpsychic  doctrine 
of  his  former  days;  and  the  "brain"  which  we  contemplate  retro- 
spectively when  we  introspect  our  (past)  psychic  states  does  not 
seem  to  be  the  same  "brain"  which  an  outsider  might  examine  with 
eye  and  hand.  I  should  not  therefore  feel  justified  in  including  him 
among  the  new  materialists,  although  many  passages  in  The  Origin 
of  Consciousness  seem  to  indicate  that  he  is  one. 

Nor  is  it  strictly  correct  to  classify  Professor  Warren  as  a  ma- 
terialist, for  he  still  clings  to  the  double-aspect  theory  of  parallel- 
ism. Yet  much  of  his  writing  on  the  mind-body  problem2  is  in  de- 
fense of  the  thesis  that  all  man's  activities  are  explicable  on  me- 
chanical or  (very  likely)  physico-chemical  principles;  so  that  in 
effect  if  not  in  name  he  is  a  defender  of  the  new  materialism.  The 
form  which  this  defensive  argument  assumes,  however,  is  a  little  dif- 
ficult to  make  out.  It  seems,  taken  in  the  large,  to  consist  of  two 
closely  related  parts.  In  the  first  place  it  maintains  that  even  the 
most  complex  forms  of  thoughtful  activity  are  built  on  the  same 
general  plan  as  ordinary  ideo-motor  action,  and  that,  inasmuch  as 
the  latter  can  be  fully  explained  mechanically,  the  highest  forms 
of  intelligent  conduct  need  no  further  explanation.  The  other  form 
of  Professor  Warren's  argument  consists  in  pointing  us  to  a  brain 
correlate  for  every  type  of  conscious  process,  including  even  the 
most  complicated  and  "intelligent." 

As  to  the  first  of  these  arguments,  it  must  be  plain  to  all  that 
the  similarity  between  ideo-motor  and  "intelligently  guided"  ac- 
tion is  accepted  and  demonstrable  only  so  far  as  it  is  irrelevant  to 
the  present  issue;  and  that  when  the  similarity  is  depicted  in  such 

»"The  Mental  and  the  Physical,"  Psy.  Sev.,  March,  1914;  "A  Study  of 
Purpose,"  thia  JOURNAL,  Jan.  and  Feb.,  1916;  "The  Mechanics  of  Intelli- 
gence, ' '  Phil.  Review,  Nov.,  1917 ;  « '  Mechanism  vertu*  Vitalism, ' '  Phil.  Review, 
Nov.,  1918. 


THE  NEW  MATERIALISM  341 

terms  as  to  make  it  relevant  to  the  issue  and  decisive,  the  presenta- 
tion of  it  as  an  actual  fact  begs  the  question.  That  there  is  a  simi- 
larity of  a  very  general  sort  between  all  forms  of  bodily  activity, 
that  they  all  have  stimulus,  central  process,  and  response,  will  be  de- 
nied by  no  one ;  but  to  assert  in  addition  to  this  that  increased  neural 
complexity  is  the  only  other  factor  involved  in  deliberately  guided 
voluntary  action  beside  what  one  finds  in  automatic  reaction  is  to 
start  with  the  conclusion  which  was  to  be  proved.  Professor  War- 
ren seeks  to  make  the  transition  from  automatic  to  intelligent  ac- 
tivity easier  by  using  voluntary  action  in  a  purely  perceptual  situa- 
tion as  a  middle  term.  In  action  of  this  sort  the  stimulus  is  an  im- 
mediately perceived  object  to  which  we  react,  as  we  do  in  thought- 
less ideo-motor  action.  On  the  other  hand  even  highly  complex  and 
thoughtful  activity  such  as  chess-playing,  which  involves  both  in- 
vention and  intelligent  adjustment  to  new  situations,  is  analogous 
to  perceptual  reaction.  "An  intelligent  reaction  based  upon  thought 
is  essentially  the  same  as  the  reaction  to  a  perceived  situation.  The 
mental  reconstruction  is  no  different  in  character  from  the  recon- 
struction of  experience  which  is  involved  in  a  changing  perceptual 
experience.  .  .  .  When  one  reacts  to  a  perceptual  stimulus  one's 
motor  activity  is  due  to  the  fact  that  a  certain  physical  collocation 
of  particles  exists  and  affects  him;  which  means  that  his  receptor 
apparatus  is  fitted  to  receive  the  impression  of  this  collocation  and 
that  appropriate  nervous  pathways  are  established  for  reaction  to 
such  impressions.  The  same  is  true  where  the  stimulus  is  a  thought- 
complex;  here  one  is  reacting  to  certain  definite  represented  physi- 
cal collocations.  Thought  is  merely  an  enlargement  of  the  per- 
ceptual field.  Intelligence  means  'fit'  reaction  to  environmental 
situations,  whether  perceived  or  pictured."3 

Now  while  both  complex  intelligent  activity  such  as  chess-play- 
ing, and  also  ideo-motor  action  have  doubtless  certain  things  in 
common  with  intelligent  reaction  to  a  perceived  situation,  it  is  plain 
also  that  in  certain  things  they  differ  from  it.  The  opponent  of 
materialism,  who  believes  in  the  efficacy  of  consciousness,  maintains 
that  one  of  these  differences  lies  exactly  in  this:  that  conscious 
thought  aids  to  some  extent  in  guiding  intelligent  perceptual  be- 
havior, and  that  conscious  thought  and  conscious  representations  of 
merely  possible  situations  which  are  never  physically  realized  aid 
still  more  in  guiding  the  higher  forms  of  activity  such  as  chess. 
Nor  has  Professor  Warren  said  a  single  thing  to  disprove  this  view. 
As  I  read  it,  at  any  rate,  his  attempted  reduction  of  intelligent  ac- 
tivity to  the  type  of  ideo-motor  action  either  reduces  to  a  harmless 

s "The  Mechanics  of  Intelligence,"  p.  612. 


342  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

pointing  out  of  irrelevant  similarities,  or  else  reads  into  the  com- 
parison identities  which  he  has  done  nothing  to  prove,  and  which 
can  not  be  admitted  in  advance  without  begging  the  question. 

Professor  Warren,  however,  seems  to  make  his  position  more 
persuasive  by  the  aid  of  his  second  argument.  He  of  course  does 
not  deny  that  certain  "higher"  and  more  complex  intellectual  proc- 
esses are  involved  in  such  things  as  chess-playing  than  in  mere 
ideo-motor  action.  But  in  all  these  the  really  efficient  factor  is  the 
brain  aspect  of  the  psychical  process.  It  is  the  "neural  processes 
known  introspectively  as  'thoughts'  of  future  situations"4  which 
really  govern  the  movement  of  the  chess  pieces.  Similarly  "satis- 
faction appears  to  be  the  subjective  aspect  of  a  neural  condition 
stimulated  by  systematic  processes  which  are  autonomically  in- 
duced."5 "Conscious  endeavor  to  deliberate  is  a  [neural]  set  in 
some  direction."  "Purpose"  must  not  be  taken  to  mean  a  con- 
scious desire  for  a  consciously  conceived  achievement  but  must  be 
interpreted  in  behavioristic,  and  ultimately  in  physiological  terms.8 
When  all  conscious  processes  have  been  thus  translated  into  neural 
terms,  the  explanation  of  the  most  complex  human  conduct  in  purely 
physico-chemical  principles  becomes  relatively  easy.  "The  com- 
plexity of  the  thought  process  means  that  a  large  number  of  neural 
connections  within  the  brain  are  formed  prior  to  each  play.  Intel- 
ligence means,  in  neural  terms,  that  the  less  satisfying  plays  find 
no  motor  outgo — that  only  one  out  of  many  incipient  reactions  is 
completed. ' ' 7 

It  would  be  unjust,  I  think,  to  accuse  Professor  Warren  of  beg- 
ging the  question  in  this  argument.  One  might  indeed  justifiably 
do  so  if  the  argument  be  interpreted  as  an  attempt  to  prove  ma- 
terialism. Plainly  it  proves  materialism  only  on  condition  that  we 
admit  the  neural  interpretation  of  intelligence  to  be  the  sole  proper 
interpretation ;  only  if  we  start  with  the  conclusion  that  intelligence 
as  such  has  nothing  to  do  with  action.  But  as  I  understand  Profes- 
sor Warren,  he  does  not  mean  to  have  his  argument  taken  in  so 
ambitious  a  sense.  He  wishes  merely  to  show  us  what  the  material- 
istic hypothesis  is,  to  show  that  it  is  possible  to  express  human  con- 
duct in  physico-chemical  terms  and  that  materialism  is  a  perfectly 
statable  view,  even  in  face  of  such  seemingly  intelligent  action  as 
chess-playing. 

If  this  is  Professor  Warren's  point  I  think  he  has  made  it. 

«  "The  Mechanics  of  Intelligence,"  p.  613. 

o  Ibid.,  p.  618. 

«"A  Study  of  Purpose,"  patsim;  also  "Mechanics  vt.  Vitalism,"  p.  611. 

T  "The  Mechanics  of  Intelligence,"  p.  613. 


THE  NEW  MATERIALISM  343 

Materialism  is  a  perfectly  statable  hypothesis.  The  question  still 
remains,  Is  it  true?  Is  it  or  is  the  opposing  hypothesis  true?  For 
as  Professor  Warren  recognizes,  the  anti-materialistic  view  of  in- 
telligent activity  is  also  perfectly  statable.  We  have,  in  short,  on 
our  hanols  the  two  opposing  hypotheses  that  we  have  always  had, 
and  the  difficulties  of  each  are  exactly  what  they  always  were.  The 
trouble  with  Professor  Warren's  type  of  materialism  has  always 
been  that  it  denies  the  efficiency  of  consciousness  and  thereby  gets 
itself  into  all  the  tangle  of  difficulties  faintly  suggested  in  the  be- 
ginning of  this  paper.  Nor  can  I  see  that  Professor  Warren  has 
done  anything  to  avoid  or  to  diminish  those  difficulties.  In  fact  he 
seems  at  times  not  even  to  realize  what  they  are.  At  the  close  of 
his  paper  on  "The  Mechanics  of  Intelligence"  he  deals  briefly  with 
' '  the  role  of  consciousness, ' '  and  all  he  has  to  say  as  to  the  dangers 
which  materialism  runs  in  denying  to  consciousness  all  real  effi- 
ciency is  the  following :  ' '  However  much  my  actions  may  be  deter- 
mined mechanistically  or  unconsciously  or  subconsciously,  it  is  my 
conscious  experiences — by  perceptions,  feelings,  imaginings  and 
thoughts — that  mean  life  to  me.  The  proved  value  of  consciousness 
is  the  subjective  life  which  it  furnishes  to  the  mind."8 

It  is  of  course  plain  that  this  response  does  not  even  come  in 
sight  of  the  real  difficulties  involved  in  the  denial  of  the  efficiency 
of  consciousness — difficulties  which  resulted  in  the  almost  universal 
rejection  of  materialism  twenty  years  ago.  My  conclusion,  there- 
fore, is  that,  so  far  as  Professor  Warren 's  arguments  are  concerned, 
the  new  materialism  is  in  no  better  case  than  the  old,  and  that,  like 
its  predecessor,  it  demands  of  us  an  amount  of  credulity  utterly  un- 
justifiable by  any  considerations  it  has  to  offer. 

No  one,  I  imagine,  sees  more  plainly  the  difficulties  we  have  just 
been  considering  than  Professor  Montague.  To  him,  as  to  most 
anti-materialists,  the  efficiency  of  consciousness  is  so  obvious  that 
it  is  futile  to  deny  it.  In  fact  his  position  has  so  much  in  common 
with  interaction  that  I  should  hesitate  in  calling  it  materialistic  if 
he  did  not  name  it  so  himself.  But,  in  spite  of  his  interactionist 
tendencies,  it  is  plain  that  he  chose  the  right  name.  In  his  attempt, 
then,  to  resuscitate  materialism  he  takes  quite  a  different  tack  from 
that  of  Professor  Warren.  He  goes  back  namely  to  something  like 
what  I  have  called  the  first  form  of  the  older  materialism  which 
identified  consciousness  with  brain  energy.  His  improvement  upon 
the  older  view  consists  in  giving  up  the  obviously  absurd  assertion 
that  consciousness  is  the  motion  of  brain  molecules  and  suggesting 
instead  that  it  may  be  some  form  of  potential  energy  stored  up  in 

a  p.  620. 


344  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  brain,  and  presumably  at  the  synapses.  It  was  in  this  form  that 
Professor  Montague  first  expressed  his  hypothesis  in  his  paper, 
"Are  Mental  Processes  in  Space  T"'  and  in  his  contribution10  to 
the  Essays  Philosophical  and  Psychological  in  Honor  of  William 
James,  both  published  in  1908.  The  thought  was  carried  farther, 
with  certain  cpistemological  modifications,  in  his  essay  on  "Truth 
and  Error"  in  the  New  Realism  (1912),  in  which  he  identified  con- 
sciousness with  causality.  More  recently  in  his  paper  on  "Variation, 
Heredity,  and  Consciousness"11  he  has  proposed  a  new  analysis  of 
potential  energy  which  in  his  opinion  makes  the  identification  of  it 
with  consciousness  the  more  acceptable.  According  to  this  most 
recent  suggestion,  just  as  kinetic  energy  is  motion,  potential  energy 
is  rest.  A  mass  may  move,  and  it  also  may  stick  to  the  same  spot. 
It  may  move  fast  and  it  may  also  stick  fast.  And  as  there  are 
many  degrees  of  the  fastness  with  which  a  thing  may  move,  so  there 
may  be  many  degrees  of  the  fastness  with  which  it  may  stick.  For 
this  new  concept  of  relative  immovability,  or  negative  energy,  Pro- 
fessor Montague  proposes  the  new  name  anergy.  His  thesis  now 
takes  the  form  of  asserting  that  the  anergy  present  at  the  synapses 
of  the  brain  is  to  be  identified  with  consciousness.  "When  a  vibra- 
tion-wave proceeding  over  a  sensory  nerve  is  gradually  brought  to 
a  stop  by  the  resistance  of  the  synapse,  its  energy  is  transformed 
from  a  visible  kinetic  form  to  an  invisible  and  potential  form.  As 
its  velocity  passes  through  the  zero-phase,  its  slowness  passes  through 
an  infinity-phase.  I  ask  you  to  entertain  the  suggestion  that  this 
infinity -phase  of  slowness  is  the  common  stuff  of  all  sensations  and 
that  the  critical  points  of  zero  and  infinity  through  which  the  mo- 
tion and  slowness  respectively  pass  afford  the  basis  for  that  qualita- 
tive absoluteness  and  discontinuity  that  differentiate  sensations 
from  mere  rates  of  change."  12 

Professor  Montague  has  been  at  great  pains  to  build  up  a  new 
conception  of  potential  energy  and  "anergy,"  and  it  is,  I  fear,  a 
little  unkind  and  unfriendly  to  assert  that  in  all  this  he  has  done 
nothing  to  make  the  identification  of  consciousness  with  brain  en- 
ergy any. easier.  Nevertheless,  that  is  the  conclusion  to  which  I  am 
driven.  It  may  perhaps  be  true  that  some  of  the  difficulties  which 
the  imagination  feels  in  identifying  consciousness  with  moving 
molecules  is  avoided  if  instead  we  tuck  it  away  quietly  in  the  sy- 
napses where  it  may  be  out  of  sight,  and  make  it  less  obtrusive  to 

•Moni*.  XVIII,  pp.  21-29. 

10 ' '  Consciousness  as  a  Form  of  Energy. ' ' 

>i  Procecdinfft  of  the  Arittotelian  Society  for  1990,  pp.  13-50. 

12  Op.  cit.,  p.  42. 


THE  NEW  MATERIALISM  345 

the  mind 's  eye  by  keeping  it  very  quiet  at  many  degrees  of  motion- 
lessness.  But  in  the  last  analysis  it  is  really  as  impossible  to  put 
meaning  into  the  assertion  that  consciousness  is  rest  as  into  the  as- 
sertion that  it  is  motion.  Once  and  for  all,  by  our  psychic  states 
we  mean  one  thing,  and  by  the  physical  states  of  our  brains  we 
mean  another;  and  it  makes  no  difference  whether  these  latter  be 
interpreted  as  motion  or  as  rest,  as  quantitative  or  qualitative,  as 
kinetic  or  potential,  as  energy  or  anergy.  I  hasten  to  point  out 
that  Professor  Montague  foresaw  just  this  criticism  and  has  left 
no  stone  unturned  to  find  an  answer  to  it.  In  the  first  place  he 
points  out  that  his  view  of  matter  and  of  mind  are  very  different 
from  that  of  Descartes;  that  matter  should  be  conceived  as  posses- 
sing the  secondary  as  well  as  the  primary  qualities ;  and  that  ' '  each 
man  feels  his  consciousness  to  pervade  not  only  his  body  but  the 
outer  space  in  which  objects  appear. "  13  If  the  limits  of  this  article 
permitted  it  would  be  possible  to  show  that  both  of  these  assertions 
would  be  very  hard  to  prove,  and  a.  theory  which  rested  upon  them 
would  be  in  much  the  same  predicament  as  that  of  a  house  built 
upon  the  sand.  As  to  the  latter  assertion  especially,  one  wonders 
whether  in  Professor  Montague's  opinion  the  potential  energy  in 
the  synapses  of  my  cortex,  which  is  identical  with  my  consciousness, 
also  "pervades  the  outer  space  in  which  objects  appear."  It  is  not 
necessary  for  our  present  purposes,  however,  to  go  into  these 
matters;  for  even  if  we  present  Professor  Montague  with  all  the 
secondary  qualities  he  wishes  for  his  material  world  and  endow  his 
consciousness  (and  also  his  cortex)  with  the  magical  power  of  per- 
vading all  spa,ce,  the  identification  of  thought  with  brain  energy 
would  still  be  as  absurd  as  ever.  All  the  secondary  qualities  and 
all  the  pervasion  of  space  imaginable  will  not  help  us  in  the  least 
to  see  how  his  thought  of  Julius  Caesar  can  be  a  certain  amount  of 
anergy  in  his  frontal  or  occipital  lobes.  Professor  Montague  argues 
that  if  we  accept  his  non-Cartesian  view  of  space  and  conscious- 
ness, "then  the  change  of  the  kinetic  energy  of  the  stimulus  into 
the  potential  energy  of  the  sensation  will  not  be  a  mysterious  change 
of  sheer  quantity  into  quality. ' ' 14  This  may  be  admitted,  and  the 
more  willingly  since  it  completely  misses  the  point  of  the  objection 
and  still  fails  to  put  any  meaning  into  the  identification  of  con- 
sciousness with  a  "qualitative  form  of  stress"  in  the  brain  synap- 
ses. Nor  does  it  help  matters  to  identify  consciousness,  as  Profes- 
sor Montague  proposes  to  do,  with  the  "higher  phases  of  intensive 
energy. ' ' 15  Finally  the  series  of  analogies  which  are  pointed  out 

is  ' '  Consciousness  as  a  Form  of  Energy, ' '  p.  120. 

!•»  Op.  cit.,  p.  131. 

is  Op.  cit.,  pp.  131-132;   "Are  Mental  Processes  in  Space!"     pp.  27-28. 


310  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

in  several  of  Professor  Montague's  articles  between  potential  energy 
and  consciousness,  while  mildly  interesting,  are  quite  as  unpersua- 
sive  and  unimpressive  as  arguments  from  analogy  usually  prove. 
And  even  were  they  immensely  more  striking  than  they  are  they 
would  do  nothing  toward  overcoming  the  essential  impossibility  in- 
volved in  the  materialistic  position.  The  hopelessness  of  the  under- 
taking is  seen  even  by  materialists  themselves — that  is,  by  those  who 
adhere  to  what  I  have  called  the  second  form  of  materialism.  In 
Professor  Warren's  words,  "If  Professor  Montague  believes  that  po- 
tential energy  is  another  name  for  consciousness — that  the  two  are 
identical — his  assumption  seems  like  identifying  visual  surface  with 
the  mass  which  we  lift."16 

The  identification  of  consciousness  with  energy  and  the  denial 
of  the  efficiency  of  consciousness  are  the  two  horns  of  a  dilemma 
which  has  in  the  past  regularly  proved  fatal  for  materialism. 
Either  one  may  be  avoided  but  not  both.  The  two  defenders  of  the 
new  materialism  whom  we  have  thus  far  considered  chose  different 
horns  to  be  avoided.  Each  carefully  evaded  one  of  the  horns,  each 
deliberately  took  his  chance  with  the  other,  and  each,  as  I  have 
tried  to  show,  came  to  grief.  The  third  and  last  advocate  of  the 
old  faith  whose  position  we  shall  examine  is  more  wary  than  his  col- 
leagues. He  knows  the  dangerous  nature  of  both  horns  of  the  di- 
lemma and  means  to  be  transfixed  by  neither.  In  two  articles  and 
in  chapters  of  three  books17  Professor  Sellers  has  sought  to  expound 
a  view  which  (though  indeed  he  does  not  himself  explicitly  call  it 
materialism)  is,  in  its  defense  of  naturalism,  essentially  material- 
istic; and  yet  at  the  same  time  he  insists  that  consciousness  is 
neither  to  be  identified  with  matter  or  brain  energy,18  nor  to 
be  robbed  of  its  efficiency.  "Consciousness  is  not  extended  after 
the  manner  of  a  physical  thing  for  the  very  simple  reason  that  it 
is  not  a  physical  thing. " 19  "  It  is  nonsense  to  say  that  the  motion 
of  atoms  is  consciousness."20  The  function  of  consciousness  "is 
to  aid  in  the  bringing  together  of  the  parts  [of  a  neural  system] 
into  a  new  integration  by  the  cues  it  affords.  Literally  it  assists 
the  brain  to  solve  problems."21  "In  deliberation  we  have  a  Con- 
is  "The  Mental  and  the  Physical,"  Pay.  Eevvew,  XXI,  p.  83. 

"  Critical  Realism,  1916  (Chapter  IX) ;  The  Essential  of  Philosophy,  1917 
(Chapter  XXII);  "An  Approach  to  the  Mind  Body  Problem,"  Phil.  Bev.  for 
March,  1918;  "Evolutionary  Naturalism  and  the  Mind  Body  Problem,"  Mo- 
nitt  for  October,  1920;  Evolutionary  Naturalism,  1922  (Chapter  XIV). 

i»  Critica   Realism,  p.  223-24. 

"  Ibid.,  p.  244. 

20  Essentials,  p.  260. 

«" Approach  to  the  Mind  Body  Problem,"  p.  158.  See  also  pp.  157  and 
159. 


THE  NEW  MATERIALISM  347 

scions  process  of  survey,  selection  and  combination.  Ideas  are  led 
to  their  consequences  and  judged  by  them.  And  our  decision  cer- 
tainly takes  the  form  of  a  plan  which  guides  our  behavior  and  with- 
out which  our  actions  would  be  quite  different. ' ' 22 

Professor  Sellars  believes  that  his  doctrine  is  able  to  avoid  the 
two  great  difficulties  of  the  older  materialism  (which  we  have  been 
discussing  in  this  paper)  and  yet  to  maintain  a  strict  naturalism; 
and  that  it  can  do  this  by  means  of  two  advances  which  thought 
has  made  in  our  century.  One  of  these  is  a  more  adequate  episte- 
mology  than  was  possessed  by  former  defendants  of  materialism, 
the  other  a  new  view  of  the  nature  of  matter  and  its  varied  ' '  levels. ' ' 

Critical  realism,  in  contrast  both  to  naive  realism,  to  neo-real- 
ism,  and  to  idealism,  identifies  consciousness  with  the  whole  field  of 
the  individual's  experience  and  at  the  same  time  insists  upon  the 
reality  and  the  knowability  of  the  physical.  Consciousness  is  that 
which  can  be  immediately  experienced — or  rather  it  is  immediate 
experience;  whereas  the  physical  world  is  never  directly  intuited 
(as  naive  realism  believes)  and  yet  (contrary  to  the  assertion  of 
idealism)  it  can  be  indirectly  known.23  This  physical  world,  more- 
over, modern  science  seems  to  show,  is  not  organized  on  simply  one 
plan,  nor  subject  to  merely  one  set  of  laws.  "If  evolution  is  more 
than  appearance,  it  surely  implies  a  change  in  the  mode  of  activity 
of  parts  of  nature. "  24  "  It  is  no  longer  possible  for  a  fair  critic  to 
identify  naturalism  with  the  mechanical  view  of  the  world."25 

The  new  and  true  naturalism  is,  therefore,  evolutionary  natural- 
ism. It  must  be  remembered,  however,  that  it  is  the  material  world 
that  is  evolving,  and  that  the  new  laws  of  action  on  its  higher  levels 
are  still  the  laws  of  the  material  world,  nor  can  it  be  admitted  by  the 
defender  of  evolutionary  naturalism  that  on  any  of  these  levels  any- 
thing independent  of  the  physical  interferes  with  the  regular  physi- 
cal activities.  Anything  like  interaction  between  consciousness 
and  the  brain  is  strongly  repudiated.  The  physical  world  is  a 
closed  system.20  The  laws  of  action  of  the  lower  material  levels, 
moreover,  are  not  abrogated.  The  new  categories  which  apply  to 
the  new  levels  are  continuous  with  the  old  ones  and  must  not  con- 

22  Evolutionary  Naturalism,  p.  312.     See  also  pp.  311  and  313.     Cf.  also 
Critical  Realism,  238,  249-50;  "Evolutionary  Naturalism"  in  the  Monist,  p.  590.. 

23  Critical  Eealism,  pp.  215-17,  247;  "Approach,"  pp.  155-56.    Ex.  Natural- 
ism, pp.  294-95,  303-05,  307,  310. 

24  Crit.  Realism,  235. 

25 Ev.  Nat.,  p.  19.    See  also  pp.  292,  297,  302,  all  of  Chapter  I;  in  fa«t  the 
whole  volume  is  devoted  to  this  contention.    See  also  "Approach,"  p.  159. 
26  Ev.  Nat.,  p.  314. 


348  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

flict  with  them.21  The  old  laws  must  be  obeyed,  the  new  ones  being 
apparently  additive  merely. 

The  question  must  of  course  immediately  present  itself  to  every 
reader:  Can  this  kind  of  modified  naturalism  be  really  compatible 
with  the  efficiency  of  consciousness?  Professor  Sellars  thinks  that 
it  can  be,  if  the  true  relation  of  consciousness  to  the  brain  be  under- 
stood. "My  thesis  is  that  the  living  organism,  when  properly  and 
adequately  conceived,  includes  consciousness."28  "When  the  cor- 
tex functions,  consciousness  forms  part  of  the  nature  of  the 
brain. ' '  *•  The  brain  has  at  least  two  ' '  variants, ' '  one  of  them 
neural  activity,  the  other  conscious  content.  Consciousness  is  thus 
a  "variant"  of  the  brain.80  "Psychical  entities  are  not  substances, 
but  rather  peculiar  characteristics  of  neural  wholes  and  insepar- 
able from  them. " S1  "  Consciousness  is  the  brain  become  con- 
scious. "82 

This  identification  of  consciousness  with  the  brain  does  not, 
in  Professor  Sellars 's  opinion,  involve  the  logical  inconsistencies  of 
the  older  materialism;  for  "we  do  not  mean  that  the  same  categor- 
ies are  applicable  to  the  physical  as  known  by  the  physical  sciences 
and  to  consciousness."  "As  classes  thought  about  by  scientists, 
the  physical  and  the  psychical  have  contradictory  attributes.  This 
must  not  be  confused  with  the  question  whether  the  physical  as  an 
existent  can  absorb  consciousness."38  In  other  words,  Professor 
Sellars  does  not  identify  consciousness  as  such  with  brain  substance 
or  brain  activity  as  such;  but  both  consciousness  and  brain  activity 
are  variants  of  one  organism.  He  simply  means  that  "conscious- 
ness is  not  alien  to  the  physical. ' ' 34  The  brain  thinks. 

We  may  be  able  to  go  all  this  way  with  Professor  Sellars  and 
still  be  unable  to  see  any  real  answer  to  the  question  how  natural- 
ism is  to  be  made  compatible  with  the  efficiency  of  consciousness. 
Consciousness  and  the  neural  activity  which  controls  our  muscles 
and  our  conduct  may  well  be  two  "variants"  of  the  organism;  but 
if  this  be  proposed  as  an  answer  to  our  question,  the  old  difficulty 

2T" Approach,"  p.  154. 

""Approach,"  p.  152. 

2»  Critical  Bealism,  p.  247.  See  also  pp.  228-29,  231;  Ev.  Nat,,  pp.  298, 
308;  Essential*,  pp.  264-65. 

so « « When  we  call  it  a  variant  of  the  brain  we  imply  that  it  is  inseparable 
from  the  brain  and  penetrates  it  with  right  as  a  part  of  the  reality  of  the 
brain."  Crit.  Bealism,  p.  244. 

«i  Ev.  Nat.,  pp.  316  and  317. 

**Crit.  Bealism,  p.  245. 

»8  Ibid.,  pp.  228,  229. 

»« Ibid.,  Chapter  IX. 


THE  NEW  MATERIALISM  349 

breaks  out  again  in  the  further  question,  What  is  the  relation  of 
these  two  ''variants"  to  each  other?  The  answer  proposed  by 
parallelism,  that  they  are  two  parallel  aspects  of  one  reality  and 
that  they  run  along  with  no  mutual  influence,  Professor  Sellars  ex- 
plicitly and  repeatedly  rejects;85  and  he  is,  naturally,  even  more 
determined  in  his  opposition  to  interaction.30  To  be  sure,  "con- 
sciousness literally  assists  the  brain  to  meet  new  situations,  '  '  3T  yet 
consciousness  and  the  brain  never  interact.  Interaction  would  im- 
ply, as  Professor  Sellars  points  out,  some  degree  of  independence 
on  the  part  of  consciousness,  at  least  while  it  lasts;  and  such  inde- 
pendence and  interaction  would  be  incompatible  with  naturalism. 
It  is,  indeed,  hard  to  see  how  the  denial  of  interaction  can  be  com- 
patible with  the  view  that  consciousness  "literally  assists  the 
brain"  and  "guides  behavior"  so  that  without  it  "our  actions 
would  be  quite  different."  One  way  out  of  the  difficulty  —  and  I 
confess  the  only  one  I  can  think  of  —  is  the  way  taken  by  Professor 
Montague,  namely  that  of  restoring  efficacy  to  consciousness  by 
making  it  a  form  of  neural  energy.  Something  like  this  view  in- 
deed Professor  Sellars  seems  often  to  take.  "Consciousness  is  ex- 
istentially  present  to  that  part  of  the  cortex  which  is  functioning, 
and  the  brain  's  space  is  its  space.  '  '  38  That  is,  it  is  in  the  brain, 
as  light  is  in  the  diamond  or  electricity  in  the  wire.  "There  is  no 
valid  reason  to  deny  that  consciousness  is  an  extended  manifold. 
It  arises  in  and  is  effective  in  the  physical  world.  Its  unity  is  that 
of  the  integrative  activity  of  the  brain  which  it  helps  to  direct. 
Hence  it  is  as  extended  as  the  brain  is."39  That  Professor  Sellars 
at  times  seeks  to  solve  the  difficulty  of  the  efficiency  of  conscious- 
ness through  the  identification  of  consciousness  with  the  activity 
of  the  brain  —  an  identification  which  at  other  times  he  emphatically 
denies  —  is  made  more  evident  through  his  explicit  identification  of 
the  mind  with  the  organization  of  the  brain40  and  his  occasional  im- 
plicit identification  of  conscious  processes  with  mental  processes. 
Intelligent  behavior  is  to  be  accounted  for  by  nervous  processes41 
since  mind  is  a  physical  category.  "Our  view  takes  the  sensori- 
motor  process  as  a  unit  and  holds  that  cortical  integration  of  which 
consciousness  is  an  element  is  always  genetically  continuous  with  a 


Realism,   p.   246;    Essentials,   pp.   257-58;    "Approach,"   p.    157; 
Ev.  Nat.,  pp.  289-<95. 

36  Essentials,  pp.  254-57;  Monist,  pp.  569-75;  Ev.  Nat.,  287-94. 
^  Ev.  Nat.,  p.  313. 

38  Crit.  Realism,  p.  244. 

39  Ibid.,  p.  247.     Cf.  also  pp.  245-49. 

«  Ibid.,  pp.  252-53.    Ev.  Nat.,  pp.  300-302,  315-16. 
4i  Ev.  Nat.,  p.  300. 


350  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

motor  pattern  of  the  brain.  In  other  words,  cortical  integrations 
arise  in  one  system  with  motor  tracts."42  "Psychical  entities  are 
peculiar  characteristics  of  neural  wholes  and  inseparable  from  them. 
...  As  soon  as  they  are  conceived  as  more  than  contents,  as  more 
than  they  themselves  reveal,  as  f?oon  as  they  are  given  by  them- 
selves power  to  do  things,  they  become  to  the  deceived  thinker  non- 
physical  and  alien  to  physical  reality."48  "The  brain  as  mind  is 
a  more  or  less  integrated  system  of  propensities  and  interests  which 
respond  to  the  situation  in  which  the  individual  is  placed.  And 
such  interests  must  not  be  thought  of  as  physiological  in  any  sense 
that  excludes  discriminative  appreciation.  They  are  neurological 
systems  whose  urgencies  are  inclusive  of  mental  contents.  Con- 
sciousness must  be  connected  psychophysically  with  neural  processes 
of  some  reach.  Attention  itself  can  be  understood  only  as  a  for- 
ward movement  or  passage  in  which  the  cerebral  activity  makes  its 
path.  What  we  must  seek  to  do  is  to  deepen  our  conception  of  the 
brain  as  at  once  activity  and  content.  It  is  sensori-motor,  ideo- 
motor;  it  is  a  stream  of  tendencies  lit  up  by  consciousness.  The 
brain  is  synthetic  because  it  is  active.  It  is  a  more  or  less  unitary 
process  controlled  by  the  neuronic  system  which  is  functionally 
uppermost."44 

I  can  not  say  I  am  perfectly  sure  what  these  last  quotations 
mean.  But  this  at  least  is  plain  to  me :  that  if  they  offer  a  method 
by  which  the  universality  of  naturalism  can  be  made  compatible 
with  the  efficiency  of  consciousness,  this  method  consists  exactly  in 
identifying  the  psychical  with  the  physical.  If  this  identification 
is  not  intended  by  Professor  Sellers  I  can  not  understand  either 
how  he  proposes  to  save  the  efficiency  of  consciousness  or  what  it  is 
he  means  by  interpreting  propensities,  interests,  discriminative  ap- 
preciation and  attention  as  neurological  systems  or  forward  move- 
ments of  cerebral  activity. 

In  other  words,  I  can  not  see  that  Professor  Sellers  has  done 
anything  to  help  materialism  out  of  its  old  dilemma  of  being  forced 
either  to  identify  consciousness  with  the  brain  or  to  deny  its  ef- 
ficacy. Neither  of  the  advances  he  has  made  over  his  predecessors 
of  a  former  generation  have  really  made  the  difficulty  any  less  real. 
Critical  realism  is  of  course  compatible  with  materialism ;  but  it  is 
equally  compatible  with  interaction.  Nor  does  the  existence  of 
"higher  levels"  of  matter  in  the  organic  world  give  any  real  assist- 
ance. For  even  on  these  higher  levels,  we  are  told,  nothing  can 

«  Ibid.,  p.   314. 

**Ev.  Nat.,  p.  317. 
«« Ibid.,  pp.  315-16. 


REALISM  WITHOUT  MONISM  OR  DUALISM        351 

conflict  with  the  mechanical  laws;  and  the  new  and  higher  laws  of 
these  levels  are  also  of  course  still  physical.  Neither  the  old  laws 
nor  the  new  therefore  can  be  interfered  with  or  modified  by  con- 
sciousness (unless  consciousness  itself  be  physical)  without  wreck- 
ing naturalism  and  the  whole  materialistic  scheme  quite  as  dis- 
asterously  as  interaction  ever  threatened  to  do.  Professor  Sellars 
does  not  seem  to  realize  that  the  ultimate  difficulty  of  materialism 
lies  not  in  the  kind  of  physical  laws  which  it  sets  in  absolute  con- 
trol of  mind  and  of  human  behavior,  but  in  setting  any  physical 
laws  in  absolute  control. 

Other  writers  than  those  considered  in  this  article  might  of 
course  be  added  to  the  list  of  neo-materialists.  But  the  three  we 
have  examined  are  typical  in  the  sense  that  between  them  they  seem 
to  exhaust  the  possibilities.  Professor  Warren  avoids  the  absurdity 
of  identifying  consciousness  with  brain  but  does  so  only  by  making 
consciousness  inefficient  and  thereby  committing  himself  to  conse- 
quences that  seem  equally  difficult  of  acceptance.  Professor  Monta- 
gue clings  to  the  efficiency  of  consciousness  but  only  at  the  cost  of 
calling  consciousness  a  form  of  neural  energy.  Professor  Sellars  is 
unwilling  to  commit  himself  to  either  of  these  difficulties ;  and  ends 
by  falling  a  victim  to  both.  My  conclusion  can  only  be  that  the 
new  materialism  has  failed  to  bring  forth  a  single  consideration 
that  makes  the  materialistic  hypothesis  really  easier  of  acceptance 
than  it  was  at  the  time  when  nearly  every  thinker  gave  it  up, 
twenty  years  ago. 

JAMES  BISSETT  PRATT. 

WILLIAMS  COLLEGE. 


REALISM  WITHOUT  MONISM  OR  DUALISM— II 

A  PREVIOUS  paper  discussed  the  nature  of  knowledge  involving 
JL\.  past  events.  The  paper  tried  to  show  that  the  object  of  knowl- 
edge in  such  cases  is  a  temporal  sequence  or  continuum  including 
past-present-future.  While  this  analysis  may  be  taken  on  its  own 
merits  or  demerits,  it  was  also  indicated  that  its  acceptance  renders 
unnecessary  the  epistemological  machinery  of  psychical  states  pos- 
sessed of  so-called  transcendent  capacity.  Mr.  Lovejoy's  discussion 
in  the  Essays  in  Critical  Realism  considers,  in  addition,  the  case 
of  anticipatory  thought,  judgments  involving  expectation,  forecasts, 
prediction.  He  tries  to  show  that  in  their  case,  at  least,  a  mental 
state  must  be  admitted,  a  representation  which  is  psychical  in  its 
existence.  He  also  questions  the  point  in  my  own  discussion  (con- 
tained in  the  Influence  of  Darwin,  etc.,  in  the  essay  on  "The  Experi- 


352  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

mental  Theory  of  Knowledge")  which  claims  that  such  anticipatory 
reference  is  involved  in  all  knowledge. 

In  principle,  the  problem  of  anticipatory  knowledge  introduces 
nothing  not  contained  in  the  prior  discussion  where  reference  to  the 
future  was  shown  to  be  involved  in  knowledge  involving  the  past. 
But  a  discussion  of  the  problem,  shifts  somewhat  the  points  of  em- 
phasis and  it  affords  an  opportunity  to  make  explicit  some  of  the 
implications  of  the  prior  discussion,  with  reference  especially  to 
the  place  of  verification  and  of  representation  and  ideas  in  a 
naturalistic  realism  which  involves  neither  monistic  nor  dualistic 
realism.  "We  may  first  consider  the  nature  of  representation. 

In  any  judgment  concerning  the  future  or  the  past,  there  is 
something  to  which  the  name  representation  is  appropriate.  A  pres- 
ent stone  stands  for  an  animal  living  in  the  past,  ashes,  for  a  fire 
that  has  died  down,  an  odor  for  a  flower  still  to  be  smelled,  a  sudden 
oscillation  of  a  needle  for  an  event  still  to  be  discovered,  and  so  on. 

Now  the  piece  of  rock,  the  ashes,  the  odor,  the  oscillating  needle 
are  first  of  all  things  present  in  experience  on  their  own  account, 
or  noncognitively ;  then  they  may  become  implicated  in  a  reflective 
inquiry.  We  may  ask  what  they  stand  for  or  indicate,  what  they  give 
witness  to  or  are  evidence  of,  or  what  they  portend.  In  this  situa- 
tion and  also  when  it  is  asserted  that  they  mean  or  support  a  certain 
conclusion,  they  acquire  a  representative  capacity  which  they  did 
not  inherently  possess.  The  piece  of  rock  is  still  a  piece  of  rock  but 
it  is  taken,  either  hypothetically  or  categorically  according  to  the 
stage  of  reflection  reached,  as  sign  or  evidence  of  something  else,  a 
fossil.  It  exercises  a  representative  function,  although  it  is  not  in  its 
own  existence  a  representation.  Just  so  a  poem  may  be  not  just  en- 
joyed, but  used  as  evidence  of  being  written  by  a  particular  author 
or  as  an  indication  of  a  certain  crisis  in  the  life  of  its  author;  an 
esthetic  object  in  its  first  intention  is  not  of  this  sort,  but  it  becomes 
such  when  and  if  it  enters  as  a  datum  into  a  judgment  about  some- 
thing else.  Just  so  a  board  may  become  a  sign,  a  column  of  mercury 
an  index  of  temperature,  a  spire  of  smoke  a  clew  to  fire,  a  stain  the 
evidence  of  some  chemical  reaction.  There  is  a  well-known  rhetorical 
device  by  which  a  function  is  transferred  to  a  thing,  and  we  call  the 
thing  by  the  name  of  its  function.  Just  so  we  call  sounds  or  marks 
on  paper,  words;  or  a  stone,  a  fossil ;  just  so  we  may  call  things  hav- 
ing the  representation  function,  representations.  In  the  first  case 
we  are  not  likely  to  forget  that  the  term  used  implies  a  connection, 
not  a  self-possessed  quality.  In  the  second  case,  we  too  easily  forget 
this  fact  and  get  into  trouble. 


REALISM  WITHOUT  MONISM  OR  DUALISM          353 

/ 

This  is  stated  somewhat  dogmatically  because  an  argument  is  not 
at  issue,  but  rather  a  recapitulation  of  a  criticized  position  which  it 
is  necessary  to  bear  in  mind  if  the  force  of  the  criticism  is  to  be 
estimated.  It  brings  us  to  the  question  of  "mediatism"  and  "im- 
mediatism"  in  knowledge.1 

Mr.  Lovejoy  says  that  two  opposing  views  of  the  knowledge  situ- 
ation may  "be  named  'immediatism'  and  'mediatism.'  According 
to  the  former,  whatever  kind  of  entity  be  the  object  of  knowledge, 
that  object  must  be  actually  given,  must  be  itself  the  directly  experi- 
enced datum.  According  to  the  latter  view,  it  is  of  the  essence  of 
the  cognitive  process  that  it  is  mediate,  the  object  being  never  reached 
directly,  and,  so  to  say,  where  it  lives,  but  always  through  some 
essence  or  entity  distinguished  from  it,  though  related  to  it  in  a 
special  way. " 2  To  this  statement  he  adds  the  acute  remark  that 
both  idealists  and  monistic  realists  are  immediatists.  He  conducts 
his  discussion  on  the  assumption  that  I  am  an  immediatist  in  the  sense 
denned  and  as  excluding  all  mediatism.  Then  he  has  no  difficulties 
in  finding  inconsistencies  in  my  treatment.  I  should  go  further  and 
say  that  upon  this  assumption  everything  I  have  written  about 
knowledge  is  one  huge  inconsistency. 

For,  as  the  remarks  about  representation  indicate,  wherever  in- 
ference or  reflection  comes  in  (and  I  should  not  call  anything  knowl- 
edge in  a  logical  or  intellectual  sense  unless  it  does  come  in),  there 
is,  clearly,  mediation  of  an  object  by  some  other  entity  which  points 
to  or  signifies  or  represents  or  gives  witness  to  or  evidence  of.  Never- 
theless, thought  or  inference  becomes  knowledge  in  the  complete 
sense  of  the  word  only  when  the  indication  or  signifying  is  borne 
out,  verified  in  something  directly  present,  or  immediately  experi- 
enced— not  immediately  known.  The  object  has  to  be  "reached" 
eventually  in  order  to  get  verification  or  invalidation,  and  when  so 
reached,  it  is  immediately  present.  Its  cognitive  status,  however,  is 
mediated;  that  is,  the  object  known  fulfils  some  specific  function 
of  representation  or  indication  on  the  part  of  some  other  entity. 
Short  of  verificatory  objects  directly  present,  we  have  not  knowl- 
edge, but  inference  whose  content  is  hypothetical.  The  subject- 
matter  of  inference  is  a  candidate  or  claim  to  knowledge  requiring 
to  have  its  value  tested.  The  test  is  found  in  what  is  finally  im- 
mediately present,  which  has  a  meaning  because  of  prior  mediation 
•which  it  would  not  otherwise  have. 

There  is,  I  think,  nothing  fundamentally  new  in  this  view,  al- 
though it  goes  contrary  to  the  more  usual  belief  that  knowledge  is 

1  The  immediacy  of  experience  concerns  one  of  the  reserved  questions. 

2  P.  48  of  Essays  in  Critical  Bealism. 


354  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

some  kind  of  direct  apprehension  or  perception  of  some  thing  or 
event.  There  is  a  certain  sense  in  which  Mr.  Lovejoy  is  much  more 
of  an  immediatist  than  I  am.  I  mean  that  for  him  the  psychical 
representation  is  but  an  organ  or  extraneous  means  of  grasping  or 
pointing  to  some  entity  immediately  complete  in  itself  as  an  object 
of  knowledge — as  was  pointed  out  in  the  prior  article  dealing  with 
' '  knowledge  of  the  past. ' '  While  from  my  point  of  view  the  relation, 
connection  or  mediation  of  one  thing  by  another  is  an  essential  fea- 
ture of  the  subject-matter  of  knowledge.  The  conception  is  not, 
as  was  said,  intrinsically  novel.  It  is  not  inherently  pragmatic. 
It  results  from  carrying  over  into  the  logical  theory  of  knowledge, 
the  methods  universally  adopted  at  present  by  natural  science,  or 
inquiry  into  natural  events.  It  is  as  appropriate  to  this  kind  of 
science  as  the  assumption  that  the  objects  of  knowledge  are  forms 
or  essences  which  must  be  directly  inspected,  was  to  the  Aristotelian 
science.  The  "pragmatic"  feature  comes  in  when  it  is  noted  that 
experiment  or  action  enters  to  make  the  connection  between  the 
thing  signifying  and  the  thing  signified  so  that  inference  may  pass 
from  hypothesis  to  knowledge.  It  is  then  seen  that  some  "conse- 
quences, ' '  namely  those  of  the  experiment,  are  an  integral  part  of  the 
completing  or  fulfilling  or  leading  out  of  the  "representation"  into 
final  objects.8  Thus  we  again  arrive  at  a  union  of  immediate  and 
mediate  in  knowledge,  instead  of  their  sharp  distinction. 

These  considerations  appear  pertinent  to  a  discussion  of  the 
nature  of  intellectual  anticipations,  predictions,  etc.  In  my  essay 
on  the  "Experimental  Theory  of  Knowledge,"  I  pointed  out  that 
there  is  an  internal  complication  in  such  cases ;  on  the  one  hand,  there 
is  something  indubitably  present,  say,  smoke;  on  the  other  hand, 
this  is  taken  to  mean  something  absent,  say,  fire.  Yet  it  is  not  a 
case  of  sheer  absence,  such  as  total  ignorance  would  imply.  The  fire 
is  presented  as  absent,  as  intended.  Its  subsequent  presence  is  re- 
quired in  order  to  fulfil  the  reference  of  the  smoke.  Mr.  Lovejoy 
says  that  this  presented-as-absent  is  what  epistemology  has  always 
signified  by  "representation"  (Essays  p.  51).  So  far,  so  good, 
bearing  in  mind  what  has  been  said  about  the  meaning  of  representa- 
tion. But  Mr.  Lovejoy  introduces  a  further  qualification.  I  had 
said  that  in  order  to  fulfil  the  meaning  of  what  is  given-as-present, 
the  given-as-absent  must  become  present,  and  this  involves  an  opera- 

•  Confusion  arises  sometimes,  I  think,  because  Mr.  James  accepted  an 
"immediate"  knowledge,  "acquaintance,"  and  applied  the  conception  of  transi- 
tive leading  only  to  "knowledge  about."  In  the  latter  he  did  not  emphasize 
the  experimental  production  of  consequences,  although  he  did  not  deny  it. 
Hence  follows  the  importance  of  discriminating  varieties  of  pragmatism  in 
discussing  theories  of  knowledge. 


355 

tion  which  tries  to  bring  the  inferred  fire  into  experience  in  the  same 
immediate  way  in  which  the  smoke  is  present.  Mr.  Lovejoy  denies 
the  need  of  any  operation  or  act.  He  says  that  we  may  dream  of 
a  windfall  of  fortune  about  which  one  can  do  nothing.  Of  course 
one  can,  just  as  one  may  construct  day-dreams  without  end.  But 
are  these  thoughts,  in  any  cognitive  sense,  of  the  future,  or  are  they 
just  fancies  whose  function — so  far  as  they  have  any — is  esthetic 
enrichment  of  the  present  moment?  He  also  denies  the  necessity 
of  an  act  to  bring  the  meant  object  into  actual  experience  on  the 
ground  that  the  thing  present,  smoke,  may  merely  remind  us  of  a 
past  object;  it  may  merely  beget  a  reminiscence  (p.  53).  I  should 
not  think  of  denying  this  fact.  The  claims  of  my  theory  begin 
when  we  ask  what  is  the  cognitive  status  of  this  reminder  or  reminis- 
cence. I  may  be  reminded  of  something  beautiful  which  I  have  read 
in  a  poem.  Does  this  make  the  reminder  knowledge?  Does  it  give 
the  smoke  or  the  poem  a  place  in  some  existential  landscape  ?  Does 
it  even  depend  upon  my  being  able  to  place  the  poem  with  respect 
to  its  author,  the  book  where  I  read  it  or  the  time  when  it  was  read  ? 
What  my  theory  is  after  is  precisely  the  differentia  between  a  re- 
minder or  reminiscence  which  is  esthetic  and  one  which  is  cognitive 
or  a  reminder  of  fact.  My  theory  involves  no  slurring  over  of  the 
existence  of  reminders.  It  claims  that  when  we  take  them  as  knowl- 
edge we  proceed  to  act  upon  them,  and  that  the  consequences  of  the 
acting  test  the  validity  of  the  claim  of  a  recollection  to  be  true  knowl- 
edge. Mr.  Lovejoy  may  hold  that  every  dream  and  every  reminder 
is  a  case  of  knowledge.  But  I  do  not  see  how  he  can  attribute  the 
implications  of  that  doctrine  to  a  theory  which  holds  that  some  ex- 
perienced objects  are  self-enclosed  esthetically,  and  therefore  lack 
cognitive  status.  Moreover,  his  inference  that  my  theory  is  false, 
since  we  do  not  act  upon  a  dream,  may  appear  to  some  to  throw  doubt 
upon  the  theory  that  a  dream  is  a  case  of  knowledge  rather  than  upon 
my  theory. 

In  discussing  my  criticism  of  monistic  realism,  Mr.  Lovejoy  has 
no  difficulty  in  finding  numerous  passages  which  indicate  that  I 
am  not  a  monistic  realist.  Considering  that  I  was  criticizing  monistic 
realism  for  its  monism,  his  discovery  does  not  surprise  me.  The 
converse  discovery  would  have  given  me  a  shock.  Mr.  Lovejoy  then 
argues  that  if  I  am  not  a  monistic  realist  I  must  be  a  dualistic  one. 
"That,  then,  is  the  alternative  to  which  he  [the  present  writer]  is 
limited — either  idealism  or  else  dualism A  concep- 
tion of  knowledge  which  should  be  at  once  realistic  and  monistic  is 
barred  to  him"  (E.  C.  R.,  p.  62).  Mr.  Lovejoy  appears  fond  of  the 
use  of  the  principle  of  excluded  middle.  But  this  principle  is  two- 


356  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

edged  as  well  as  sharp.  Unless  handled  carefully,  it  cuts  the  fingers 
of  the  one  who  uses  it.  We  have  already  noted  how  Mr.  Lovejoy 
makes  an  exhaustive  disjunction  between  the  immediate  and  the  medi- 
ate in  knowledge  on  the  basis  of  which  he  convicts  me  of  inconsis- 
tency. We  have  also  noted  that  the  gist  of  my  theory  about  the  object 
of  knowledge  is  that  it  is  mediate  in  one  respect  and  immediate  in 
another,  so  that  the  alleged  inconsistency  is  due  to  failure  to  grasp 
the  theory.  Neither  is  the  disjunction  between  monistic  and  dualis- 
tic  realism  exhaustive.  There  remains  pluralistic  realism,  which 
is  precisely  the  theory  I  have  advanced.  The  things  which  are 
taken  as  meaning  or  intending  other  things  are  indefinitely  diversi- 
fied, and  so  are  the  things  meant.  Smoke  stands  for  fire,  an  odor 
for  a  rose,  different  odors  for  many  different  things,  mercury  for 
atmospheric  pressure  or  heat,  a  stain  for  a  biochemical  process,  and 
so  on  ad  infinitum.  Things  are  things,  not  mental  states.  Hence  the 
realism.  But  the  things  are  indefinitely  many.  Hence  the  pluralism. 
It  all  hangs  together  with  the  hypothesis  which  has  been  outlined 
concerning  the  nature  of  knowledge.4 

Mr.  Lovejoy,  however,  has  another  shot  in  his  locker.  Since  I 
admit  that  in  anticipatory  inference — in  all  reflection  from  my  point 
of  view — something  is  present-in-experience-as-absent  and  as-to 
be-brought-into-presence-of-a-direct-kind,  he  holds  that  I  have 
admitted  the  psychical  or  mental  as  a  term  in  the  judging  process, 
and  hence  am  committed  to  dualism.  His  dialectical  argument  in 
support  of  this  view  appears  to  manifest  another  instance  of  addic- 
tion to  uncritical  use  of  the  principle  of  excluded  middle.  Present-as- 
absent,  or  the  presence  of  the  absent,  is  an  impossibility  as  regards 
any  physical  thing.  Hence  there  is  an  admission  of  a  psychical  en- 
tity. For,  he  says,  the  adjectives  mental  and  psychical  as  he  uses 
them  "simply  designate  anything  which  is  an  undubitable  bit  of 
experience,  but  [which]  either  can  not  be  described  in  physical 
terms  or  can  not  be  located  in  the  single  objective  or  '  public '  spatial 
system,  free  from  self-contradictory  attributes,  to  which  the  objects 
dealt  with  by  physical  science  belong"  (E.  C.  R.,  p.  61). 

This  assumption  of  an  exhaustive  disjunction  between  the  physi- 
cal and  psychical  is  significant.  It  disposes,  by  a  single  sweeping 
gesture,  of  the  growing  number  of  persons,  not  pragmatists,  who 

*  There  is  nothing  original  on  my  part  in  this  view.  It  is  held  by  some 
whose  realistic  standing  is  probably  less  open  to  suspicion  than  is  mine,  Profes- 
sor Woodbridge  for  example.  See  his  ' '  Nature  of  Consciousness, ' '  this  JOURNAL, 
Vol.  II,  p.  119.  He  has  drawn  some  inferences  from  this  conception  which  I 
have  found  myself  unable  to  accept,  and  I  have  drawn  some  which  I  fear  do 
not  command  his  assent.  But  I  am  glad  to  acknowledge  indebtedness  to  him 
for  much  clarification  of  my  own  thought  on  the  subject. 


357 

hold  that  certain  entities  are  neutral  to  the  distinction  of  psychical 
and  physical.  It  asserts,  by  implication,  that  all  meanings,  relations, 
activity  systems,  functions,  affairs  like  mathematical  entities, 
like  a  constitution,  a  franchise,  values,  operations,  concep- 
tions, norms,  etc.,  are  psychical.  Such  a  position  is  peculiarly 
striking  in  the  context  of  a  volume  which  makes  constant  use 
of  the  notion  of  essence.  Mr.  Lovejoy,  himself,  refers 
on  the  very  page  from  which  the  passage  is  quoted  to  "a.  common 
character  or  essence"  found  in  the  thing  representing  and  the  thing 
represented. 

From  the  standpoint  of  argument,  I  am  entitled,  I  think,  to  leave 
the  matter  here,  till  Mr.  Lovejoy  and  his  collaborators  have  wrestled 
with  the  question  of  essence  in  its  bearing  upon  the  exhaustiveness 
of  the  disjunction  between  the  physical  and  the  psychical,  and  till 
many  non-pragmatists  have  been  disposed  of.  The  situation  certainly 
puts  the  burden  of  proof  upon  Mr.  Lovejoy.  But  it  is  better  to  take 
advantage  of  this  opportunity  to  make  a  brief  restatement  of  my 
own  view  as  to  the  nature  of  "ideas"  or  the  mental.  Mr.  Lovejoy 
starts  with  a  ready-made  psychical  existence  which  assumes  the 
function  of  reference  or  of  signifying,  and  that  the  future  thing 
which  is  presented  as  absent  is,  itself,  psychical,  or  if  not  in  itself,  at 
least  in  its  presence-as-absent.  My  hypothesis  reverses  the  notion. 
It  starts  with  a  thing,  res,  actualty  present,  smoke,  rock,  and  with 
the  present  fact  that  this  something  refers  to  something  else  of  the 
same  order  of  existence  as  itself,  a  fire,  or  geologic  animal.  It  bases 
itself  upon  the  undoubted  occurrence  of  inference  from  one  present 
thing  to  another  absent  thing  of  the  same  non-psychical  kind.  It 
thus  avoids  the  breach  of  continuity,  the  dualism,  involved  in  di- 
viding existence  into  two  orders,  physical  and  psychical,  which  are 
defined  only  by  antithetical  attributes,  and  of  such  a  nature  that 
reference  and  intercourse  between  them  is  an  affair  totally  unlike 
any  other  known  matter.  It  also  has  the  advantage  of  starting 
from  a  vera  causa,  the  undubitable  fact  of  inference.5 

According  to  hypothesis,  then,  the  future  thing  meant  is  objec- 
tive— a  fire,  possibility  of  finding  additional  traces  of  extinct  organ- 
isms, a  rain  storm,  penalization  of  certain  modes  of  behavior,  or  an 
eclipse  of  the  sun.  It  is  stood  for  or  represented  by  something 
equally  objective,  mathematical  figures,  words,  heard  or  seen  things, 
etc.  That  one  objective  affair  should  have  the  power  of  standing 
for,  meaning,  another  is  the  wonder,  a  wonder  which  as  I  see  it,  is 
to  be  accepted  just  as  the  occurrence  in  the  world  of  any  other  quali- 

s  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  p.  225. 


358  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

tative  affair,  the  qualities  of  water,  for  example.6  But  a  thing 
which  has  or  exercises  the  quality  of  being  a  surrogate  of  some  ab- 
sent thing  is  so  distinctive,  so  unique,  that  it  needs  a  distinctive 
name.  As  exercising  the  function  we  mot/  caU  it  mental.  Neither 
the  thing  meant  nor  the  thing  signifying  is  mental.  Nor  is  meaning 
itself  mental  in  any  psychical,  dualistic,  existential  sense.  Tradi- 
tional dualism  takes  the  undoubted  logical  duality,  or  division  of 
labor,  between  data  and  meanings,  and  gets  into  the  epistemological 
predicament  by  transforming  it  into  an  existential  dualism,  a  separa- 
tion of  two  radically  diverse  orders  of  being.7  Starting  from  the 
undoubted  existence  of  inference,  or  from  a  logical  function,  "ideas" 
denote  problematic  objects  so  far  as  they  are  signified  by  present 
things  and  are  capable  of  logical  manipulation.  A  probable  rain 
storm,  as  indicated  to  us  by  the  look  of  the  clouds  or  the  barometer, 
gets  embodied  in  a  word  or  some  other  present  thing  and  hence  can 
be  treated  for  certain  purposes  just  as  an  actual  rain  storm  would 
be  treated.  We  may  then  term  it  a  mental  entity.  Such  a  theory,  it 
will  be  noted,  explains  the  mental  on  the  basis  of  a  logical  function. 
It  does  not  start  by  shoving  something  psychical  under  a  logical 
operation.8 

The  matter  is  so  important  that  perhaps  it  is  worth  while  to 
try  to  state  it  in  another  way.  Meanings  are  the  characteristic  things 
in  intellectual  experience.  They  are  the  heart  of  every  logical  func- 
tion. They  are  not  physical  nor  are  they  (pace  Mr.  Lovejoy's  dis- 
junction) psychical.9  A  meaning  is  not  necessarily  such  that  it  can 
be  called  an  idea  or  thought.  But  a  meaning  may  be  adopted  hypo- 
thetically,  as  a  basis  for  instituting  inquiries,  or  as  a  point  of  depar- 
ture in  connection  with  other  meanings  for  reasoning,  an  experiment 
in  combining  meanings  together  to  see  what  develops.  Such  a  tenta- 
tive acceptance  of  meanings  is  all  that  is  possible  in  a  problematic  sit- 
uation, unless  we  make  either  a  dogmatic  assertion  or  a  dogmatic 
denial.  What  is  the  meaning  of  some  event  ?  What  is  it  all  about  t 
Something  suggests  itself  as  a  possible  answer  or  solution.  It  is  as  yet, 

o  That  is  to  say,  it  is  a  metaphysical  or  cosmological  or  scientific  question — 
as  the  case  may  be — which  effects  all  schools  of  epistemological  thought  alike. 
It  is  not  a  problem  which  bears  more  heavily  on  one  than  on  another,  though 
on  the  face  of  it  there  are  more  difficulties  for  a  dualistic  school  than  for 
others  because  of  the  implied  breach  of  continuity. 

7  This  point  has  been  developed,  not  to  say  labored,  in  the  essay  entitled 
"Data  and  Meanings"  in  the  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  pp.  136-156. 

•See  the  essay  on  the  "Logical  Character  of  Ideas,"  pp.  220-229  of 
E.  E.  L. 

•  Of  course  upon  my  theory  they  are,  existentially  speaking,  the  operations 
involved  in  any  situation  having  cognitive  reference. 


REALISM  WITHOUT  MONISM  OR  DUALISM          359 

however,  only  a  possible,  a  conjectural  meaning.  How  is  it  to  pass 
beyond  conjecture  and  be  definitely  asserted  or  rejected?  Inquiry 
proceeds  by  taking  a  stand,  as  it  were,  upon  the  meaning  and  using 
it  as  a  base  for  new  observations  and  reasonings.  //  so  and  so,  then 
so  and  so.  We  look  to  see  if  the  "then  so  and  so"  can  be  actually 
presented  in  experience.  In  the  degree  in  which  we  can  thus  find 
what  is  hypothetically  demanded  and  can  determine  that  only  the 
"if  so  and  so"  implies  it,  we  make  assertion  categorical.  Such  is 
the  course  of  any  legitimate  reflection.  But  the  operation  demands 
that  the  meaning  be  embodied  in  existence,  that  it  be  a  "concretion 
in  discourse"  to  borrow  Mr.  Santayana's  apt  term.  The  usual 
method  is  a  word  or  diagram,  but  in  any  case,  there  must  be  some 
physical  thing  to  carry  the  meaning,  if  the  latter  is  to  be  employed 
for  intellectual  manipulation  and  experimentation,  or  as  an  effec- 
tive hypothesis.  The  hypothetical  meaning  thus  embodied  consti- 
tutes a  thought  or  an  idea,  a  representation. 

This  is  the  theory  which  I  have  put  forth.10  The  theory  is,  of 
course,  conceivably  incorrect.  But  if  so,  it  is  incorrect  because  of 
matters  of  fact.  It  is  not  arbitrary  nor  paradoxical,  and  while  it 
is  obviously  inconsistent  with  presentative  dualism  or  transcendent 
immediatism  it  does  not  appear  to  be  inconsistent  with  itself  when 
it  is  taken  in  its  own  terms. 

I  close  with  a  general  remark  on  the  main  point  at  issue,  the 
question  of  the  method  appropriate  to  investigation  of  the  problem 
of  knowledge.  This,  rather  than  ' '  pragmatism, ' '  is  the  point  at  issue. 
Professor  Rogers,  in  his  contribution  to  Essays  in  Critical  Realism, 
has  stated  the  matter  in  such  a  way  as  to  define  the  issue.  He  says 
"that  the  quarrel  between  the  critical  realist  and  the  pragmatist  is 
due,  primarily,  to  the  fact  that  they  are  not  dealing  with  the  same 
problem.  Professor  Dewey  's  concern  is  with  the  technique  of  the  ac- 
tual advance  of  knowledge  in  the  concrete — its  linear  dimension  in  re- 
lation to  other  knowledge  past  and  future,  as  this  enters  into  the  tex- 
ture of  conduct.  The  critical  realist,  on  the  contrary,  is  interested 
in  its  dimension  of  depth — its  ability  to  present  to  man's  mind  a 
faithful  report  of  the  true  nature  of  the  world  in  which  he  has  to 
act  and  live"  (p.  160). 

I  am  grateful  to  Professor  Rogers  for  putting  the  case  so  clearly 
from  his  point  of  view.  It  marks  a  genuine  advance  in  fruitful 
discussion.  It  gives  me  an  opportunity  to  say  that  from  my  own 
standpoint  the  quarrel  is  not  due  to  the  fact  that  we  are  discussing 
different  problems.  We  are  discussing  the  same  problem.  The 

"  See,  in  addition  to  references  already  given,  pp.  430-433  of  Essays  in 
Experimental  Logic. 


360  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

difference  concerns  the  method  by  which  the  problem  is  to  be  ap- 
proached and  dealt  with.  The  objection  is  to  the  epistemological 
method  as  distinct  from  a  method  which  accepts  logical  procedure 
as  a  fact  and  then  tries  to  analyze  it.  My  contention  is  that  the 
problem  of  a  faithful  report  of  the  world  in  which  we  have  to  act 
and  live  can  be  fruitfully  approached  only  by  means  of  an  inquiry 
into  the  concrete  procedure  by  which  actual  knowledge  is  secured  and 
furthered.  In  most  matters,  we  have  painfully  learned  that  the 
way  to  arrive  at  a  sound  generalization  is  by  examination  and  analy- 
sis of  specific,  concrete  cases.  Why  not  apply  this  lesson  of  scientific 
procedure  to  the  problem  of  reaching  a  conception  of  knowledge,  to 
the  problem  of  the  nature  of  a  faithful  report  of  the  world!  If  we 
do  enforce  this  lesson,  the  disjunction  between  the  critical  realist's 
problem  and  the  "pragmatist's"  problem,  as  stated  by  Mr.  Rogers, 
vanishes. 

What  does  "faithful"  denote  and  signify?  What  does  "report" 
denote  and  signify?  And,  more  important  still,  by  what  method 
shall  we  seek  an  answer  to  these  questions?  Mr.  Pratt  in  his  contri- 
bution quotes  a  saying  of  Mr.  Santayana's  that  "an  opinion  is  true 
if  what  it  is  talking  about  is  constituted  as  the  opinion  asserts  it  to 
be  constituted"  (p.  99  of  E.  C.  R.).  With  all  my  heart;  assent  can 
not  be  too  unqualified.  But  is  the  statement  a  solution  or  does  it 
contain  the  gist  of  a  problem?  What  is  an  opinion,  existentially 
speaking,  and  what  does  it  mean?  And  so  of  the  terms  "talking 
about,"  "assert,"  and  so  of  the  connection  between  the  talking  about 
and  the  "what"  talked  about,  implied  in  the  term  "as."  These  are 
things  to  be  investigated  if  we  are  to  reach  a  satisfactory  conclusion 
concerning  the  nature  of  a  faithful  report.  And  I  see  no  way  to 
answer  them  except  to  adopt  the  same  procedure  which  we  employ 
in  investigating  other  subject-matters :  analyze  special  cases  of  knowl- 
edge secured  and  advanced,  and  generalize  the  outcome  of  the  analy- 
sis. My  objection  to  the  epistemological  method  is  that  it  ignores 
the  only  method  which  has  proved  fruitful  in  other  cases  of  inquiry; 
that  it  does  so  because  it  accepts,  uncritically,  an  old  and  outworn 
psychological  tradition  about  psychical  states,  sensations  and  ideas,11 
and  because,  in  so  doing,  it  states  the  problem  in  a  way  which  makes 
it  insoluble  save  by  the  introduction  of  a  mysterious  transcendence 
plus  a  naive  confidence  in  irresistible  propensities  and  unescapable 
assumptions.  And  when  it  comes  to  any  particular  case  of  alleged 
knowledge  we  find  the  epistemologists  abandoning  their  epistemo- 
logical machinery  and  falling  back  upon  the  logical  procedure  ac- 

»  See  an  article  in  this  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XI,  p.  505. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  361 

tually  employed  in  critical  investigations  which  terminate  in  experi- 
mental verifications.    Why  not  begin,  then,  at  this  point  ? 

We  are  trying  to  know  knowledge.  The  implication  assuredly 
is  that  there  is  knowledge.  The  procedure  which  I  have  tried  to 
follow,  no  matter  with  what  obscurity  and  confusion,  is  to  begin 
with  cases  of  knowledge  and  to  analyze  them  to  discover  why  and 
how  they  are  knowledges.  If  this  procedure  can  be  successfully 
undertaken,  then  we  can  tell  what  knowledge  is.  What  other 
method  is  reasonable?  We  are  trying,  be  it  remembered,  to  know 
knowledge,  to  get  at  and  formulate  its  character.  What  is  the 
likelihood  of  success  in  the  undertaking  if  we  rule  out  specific  cases 
of  knowledge  and  try  to  investigate  knowledge  at  large  ?  If  we  have 
no  case  of  knowledge  upon  which  to  go,  and  upon  which  to 
base  judgments  as  to  the  value  of  a  preferred  knowledge  of 
knowledge,  what  meaning  has  the  term  knowledge?  Why  not 
call  it  abracadabra,  or  splish-splosh,  or  anything  else  that 
comes  into  your  head?  How  does  knowledge,  at  the  best, 
mean  something  different  from  poesy  or  fancy  or  dreams?  For  my 
part  if  we  wish  to  know  what  a  faithful  report  of  the  world  in  which 
we  live  means,  I  prefer  to  take  the  best  authenticated  cases  of  faith- 
ful reports  which  are  available,  compare  them  with  the  sufficiently 
numerous  cases  of  reports  ascertained  to  be  unfaithful  and  doubtful, 
and  see  what  we  find.  Starting  in  this  way,  we  have  a  method  by 
which  we  can  also  discriminate  and  identify  poesy,  reverie,  dreams, 
sensations,  ideas,  hypotheses,  data,  and  all  the  rest  of  it.  The  prin- 
ciple of  parsimony  has  claims  which  all  tell  in  behalf  of  the  use  of 
the  logical  method. 

JOHN  DEWEY. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  Absolute  Relations  of  Time  and  Space.    ALFRED  A.  ROBB.     Cam- 
bridge University  Press.     1921.     Pp.  viii  +  80. 
This  little  book  is  a  simplified  summary  of  the  author's  earlier 
work,  A  Theory  of  Time  and  Space.    It  amounts,  I  should  say,  to 
a  restatement  of  the  special  theory  of  relativity,  in  which  an  at- 
tempt is  made,  first,  to  avoid  paradox  as  far  as  possible,  and  secondly, 
to  reduce  all  the  geometrical  concepts  involved  to  a  single  undefined 
relation.     In  the  former  respect,  the  success  of  the  work  may  be 
doubted ;  in  the  latter  respect  its  success  is  altogether  brilliant. 

Mr.  Robb  is  one  of  those  who  has  revolted  against  the  notion  that 
what  is  the  earlier  of  two  events  for  one  observer  can  be — and  not 


362  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

merely  seem  to  be — the  later  of  the  two  for  another  observer.  This 
seems  to  him  to  make  the  relation  of  before  and  after  merely  sub- 
jective, whereas  science  requires  that  it  be  objective.  The  objection 
appears  to  me  to  be  unsound,  for  it  leaves  out  of  account  the  fact 
that  the  difference  in  the  temporal  relations  of  the  two  observers  is 
supposed,  according  to  the  theory  criticized,  to  have  a  perfectly  def- 
inite objective  basis.  And,  on  examination,  the  difference  between 
Einstein  and  our  author  shows  itself  to  be  merely  verbal.  All 
the  complexity  of  multitudinous  time-systems  which  Einstein  recog- 
nizes appears  again  here  under  the  veil  of  a  new  terminology. 

Mr.  Robb's  starting-point  is  the  assumption  that  for  an  event  A 
to  be  earlier  than  an  event  B,  it  must  be  possible  for  A  to  be  among 
the  causal  antecedents  of  B;  that  is  to  say,  it  must  be  possible  for  a 
physical  influence  starting  from  A  to  reach  the  place  of  B  not  later 
than  B.  If  now  we  suppose  that  there  is  a  maximum  speed  with 
which  energy  can  be  transmitted — the  velocity  of  light — and  if  we 
compare  events  at  two  different  points  in  space,  there  will  be  at 
either  point  a  time-interval  within  which  the  events  will  be  neither 
earlier  nor  later  than  a  given  instantaneous  event  at  the  other  point. 
As  the  distance  increases,  the  time-interval  increases  also.  The  whole 
period  of  the  Great  War  may  be  neither  earlier  nor  later  than  a 
given  event  on  Sirius.  Contrariwise,  as  what  we  may  call  the  "neu- 
tral interval"  varies,  the  distance  must  vary.  Thus  spatio-temporal 
relations  exhibit  a  sort  of  "conical  order."  Now  it  is  only  when, 
according  to  Einstein,  A  precedes  B  in  all  time-systems,  that,  ac- 
cording to  Mr.  Robb,  A  is  said  to  precede  B.  Thus  a  certain  amount 
of  paradox  is  avoided.  But  an  equal  paradox  is  substituted.  We 
are  not  to  speak  of  the  same  instant  as  occurring  throughout  the 
universe.  Each  instant  is  restricted  to  a  certain  point  of  space. 
Is  anything  gained  for  science  or  common  sense  T 

But  if  Mr.  Robb's  terminology  is  not  less  paradoxical  than  Ein- 
stein 's,  it  is  equally  legitimate ;  and  it  leads  to  the  brilliant  piece  of 
logical  analysis  which  I  have  mentioned.  The  fact  that  each  time- 
interval  is  correlative  with  a  certain  distance  enables  Mr.  Robb  to 
provide  a  set  of  definitions  of  geometrical  concepts  in  terms  of  the 
relations  of  before  and  after.  In  Mr.  Robb's  own  words,  "spatial 
relations  are  to  be  regarded  as  the  manifestation  of  the  fact  that  the 
elements  of  time  form  a  system  in  conical  order."  It  is  not  easy  to 
do  justice  to  the  ingenuity  with  which  this  analysis  is  conceived; 
and  it  is  safe  to  say  that  the  subject  is  given  a  clearing-up  which  no 
other  mode  of  treatment  could  well  surpass. 

THEODORE  DE  LACUNA. 

BRTN*  MAWR  COLLECT. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS         363 

JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  AMERICAN  JOURNAL  OF  PSYCHOLOGY.  January, 
1922.  Instinct  and  Value  (pp.  1-18)  :  HENRY  C.  LiNK.-The  mech- 
anistic, pseudo-scientific  and  popular  definitions  of  instinct  are  pre- 
sented with  the  conclusion  that  as  long  as  the  present  vague  and 
varied  notions  prevail,  no  definite  conclusions  can  be  drawn  as  to 
their  relation  to  value  and  that  when  instincts  are  defined  more  ac- 
curately and  carefully  more  accurate  correlations  between  them 
and  values  will  be  possible.  The  Psychology  of  Reflex  Action  (pp. 
19-^12)  :  J.  R.  KANTOR.-Reflexes  can  best  be  understood  when  con- 
sidered as  psychological  acts  rather  than  physiological  acts.  This 
gives  them  their  place  in  the  adaptations  of  the  organism.  Func- 
tional Psychology  and  the  Psychology  of  Act:  II  (pp.  43-83)  :  E. 
B.  TiTCHENER.-The  discussion  begins  with  an  analysis  of  Brentano's 
works  and  the  criticisms  of  Meinong,  Husserl  and  Miinsterberg. 
They  agree  that  consciousness  is  "intentional."  This  intentional 
psychology  is  closely  affiliated  to  philosophy  and  education.  Af- 
firmation and  Negation  (pp.  84-96)  :  C.  H.  GRiFrrrs.-This  experi- 
mental study  shows  that  affirmative  instructions  can  be  more  easily 
and  quickly  followed.  This  indicates  that  negation  is  a  different 
neurological  process  from  affirmation.  Comparative  Cognitive  Re- 
action-Time with  Lights  of  Different  Spectral  Character  and  at  Dif- 
ferent Intensities  of  Illumination  (pp.  97-112) :  MARTHA  ELLIOTT.- 
Reaction  times  vary  directly  with  intensity  with  maximum  effi- 
ciency between  10  foot-candles  and  20  foot-candles.  The  Miracle 
Man  of  NeuT  Orleans  (pp.  113-120)  :  JOHN  M.  FLETCHER.-This 
miracle  man  attracted  great  crowds  but  the  public  soon  lost  confi- 
dence in  his  ability.  In  the  realm  of  mental  diseases  indefensible 
practices  such  as  represented  in  this  case  still  flourish.  An  Experi- 
mental Study  of  the  Perception  of  Oiliness  (pp.  121-127) :  LILLIAN 
WEST  COBBEY  AND  ALICE  HELEN  SuLLivAN.-Oiliness  is  a  fusion  of 
warmth  and  light  pressure.  Minor  Studies  from  the  Psychological 
Laboratory  of  Cornell  University.  LV.  Cutaneous  Localization  and 
the  "Attribute  of  Order"  (pp.  128-134)  :  H.  M.  LuFKiN.-The 
study  suggests  that  localization  is  in  general  a  matter  of  perception 
rather  than  sensation.  LVI.  On  the  Non-Visual  Perception  of  the 
Length  of  Vertically  Whipped  Rods  (pp.  135-139) :  ERNA  SHULTS.- 
The  perception  of  length  depends  upon  the  relative  intensity  of 
two  opposed  pressure  experiences  in  the  hand.  LVII.  On  the 
Non-Visual  perception  of  the  Length  of  Horizontally  Whipped  Rods 
(pp.  139-144)  :  A.  S.  BAKER.-The  perception  of  the  length  hori- 
zontally whipped  rods  is  more  accurate  than  that  for  vertically 
whipped  rods.  This  perception  depends  on  the  experience  of  op- 


364  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

posed  pressures.  Reviews  of  Books.  Oswald  Kuelpe,  Vorlesungen 
iiber  Psychologic:  R.  M.  OGDEN.  Charles  Baudouin,  Suggestion 
and  Aiitfisiujui'stidn:  MARGARET  FLOY  WASHBURN.  Wilhelm 
\Vuiidt,  Elcintnts  of  Folk  Psychology:  E.  B.  T.  Wesley  Raymond 
Wells,  The  Biological  Foundations  of  Belief:  L.  B.  HOISINGTON. 
L.  A.  Averill,  Psychology  for  Normal  Schools:  H.  G.  BISHOP.  Notes. 
Benno  Erdmann :  RAYMOND  DODGE.  Festschrift  for  Carl  Sturapf : 
E.  B.  T.  The  Edinburgh  Meeting  of  the  British  Association.  H. 
S.  LANGPELD. 

Sortais,  Gaston.     La  Philosophic  moderne  depuis  Bacon  jusqu'a 
Leibniz.    Vol.  II.    Paris :  P.  Lethielleux.    1922.    Pp.  584.    20  f r. 

Poyer,  Georges.     Les  Problemes  generaux  de  1'Heredite  psycholo- 
gique.    Paris:  Felix  Alcan.    1921.     Pp.  302.    15  fr. 

Baudin,   E.     Psychologic.     Third   edition.     Paris:   J.  de  Gigord. 
1921.    Pp.  630. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

A  correspondent  has  sent  us  the  following  questions,  which 
formed  part  of  an  examination  given  in  1893  to  prospective  teachers 
of  Ohio : 

1.  Name  the  three  primary  divisions  of  the  mind  and  give  an 
outline  (divisions  and  subdivisions)   of  the  first  division. 

2.  Distinguish  between  soul  and  spirit  and  show  how  the  former 
controls,  influences,  and  wields  the  body. 

3.  What  is  consciousness?     Show  in  how  many  ways  it  is  ex- 
ercised. 

Dr.  Charles  E.  Cory  has  been  promoted  from  associate  professor 
to  professor  of  philosophy  at  Washington  University,  St.  Louis. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  14  JULY  6,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  DICHOTOMY  OF  NATURE 

ONE  of  the  oldest  ways  of  construing  the  universe  is  to  see  it 
made  up  by  pairs  of  opposites.  Matter  and  motion,  good  and 
evil,  art  and  science,  structure  and  function,  life  and  the  non-living, 
are  obvious  couples  of  this  sort;  the  list  can  be  extended  almost  in- 
definitely without  going  far  from  common  sense.  If  it  is  the  custom 
of  modern  philosophy  to  make  little  of  these  dualities,  let  us  remem- 
ber that  years  of  epistemological  controversy,  training  the  devotee 
to  the  very  pink  of  specialization  and  sophistication,  have  doubtless 
atrophied  the  power  of  seeing  the  obvious  or  of  appreciating  the  sig- 
nificant. Philosophers  of  the  past,  indeed,  have  noted  them  often 
enough.  The  Pythagoreans  are  said  to  have  arranged  the  universe 
on  such  a  pattern,  and  Heraclitus  found  in  opposition  the  genesis 
of  reality.  Plato's  fundamental  dualism,  and  the  Aristotelian  act 
and  potency,  applied  unwaveringly  by  the  scholastics,  continued 
the  tradition.  In  the  coincidentia  oppositorum  of  Nicolaus  Cusanus, 
the  old  tendency  reappears,  and  in  the  first  period  of  modern  philoso- 
phy the  duality  of  mind-body  was  the  bone  of  contention.  Unfor- 
tunately, the  philosopher's  attention  was  soon  turned  into  the 
narrow  channel  of  the  problem  of  knowledge  and  the  study  of 
reality  languished.  But  eventually  Hegel,  whose  merit  lay  in  his 
profoundly  objective  interest,  brought  philosophy  back  to  the  normal 
point  of  view  by  presenting  a  map  of  the  universe  built  out  of  pairs 
in  an  ascending  scale.  Yet  because  he  made  certain  mistakes  in  his 
classification,  his  successors  have  tended  to  view  askance  the  two- 
fold habit  of  nature  which  he  dwelt  upon ;  whereby  they  have  lost  a 
deal  of  empirical  truth.  At  any  rate,  it  seems  clear  that  this  trait  of 
reality,  so  frequently  noticed,  so  ubiquitous,  so  momentous  in  human 
concerns,  is  likely  to  possess  high  metaphysical  significance.  Let 
us  then  set  forth  a  list  of  the  pairs  which  we  find  in  the  universe,  and 
examine  their  meaning  and  connections.  We  shall  find  that  they 
display  a  striking  unity  of  plan,  and  one  which,  I  venture  to  think, 
furnishes  the  key  to  some  old  mysteries. 

We  begin  with  a  few  cautions.  The  categories  that  follow  are  to 
be  taken  as  matrices  rather  than  polished  gems ;  thought  may  carve 
them  into  sharp-edged  concepts,  yet  in  reality  a  category  is  (to  vary 
the  figure)  a  bright  spot  with  luminous  rays  extending  to  other 

365 


:>,«,<,  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

bright  spots,  though  not  equally  in  all  directions,  and  perhaps  in 
some  falling  quite  short.  It  need  not  be  cut  off  clean  from  the  rest, 
to  be  real  for  itself.  Nor  shall  we  proceed  at  once  to  the  other  ex- 
treme and  declare  that  all  categories  are  but  abstractions  from  a  con- 
tinuous manifold.  If  they  are  in  any  sense  abstract,  it  is  nature  and 
not  man  that  does  the  abstracting;  at  least  in  many  cases  we  shall 
find  this  to  be  so.  And  we  use  "category"  here  in  a  very  general  sense, 
to  mean  a  habit  of  nature  frequent  enough  to  seem  metaphysically  im- 
portant. We  do  not  refuse,  as  Mr.  Alexander  does,  to  call  quality 
a  category.  Technical  accuracy,  requisite  indeed  for  some  purposes, 
is  not  our  present  aim.  One  can  point  out  a  tree  in  the  landscape, 
and  discourse  truthfully  and  significantly  about  it,  without  rule  or 
compass;  and  perhaps  the  same  is  true,  mutatis  mutandis,  of  meta- 
physical discourse.  And  finally,  it  is  perhaps  well  to  say  that  we  are 
not  attempting  to  deduce  the  categories  from  some  beginning ;  we  do 
but  expound  a  plan  which  nature  seems  to  offer,  and  of  which  we 
are  the  passive  spectators. 

The  first  pair  is  that  of  things  and  relations  between  them.  We 
place  it  first  because  this  is  the  simplest,  vaguest,  and  widest-spread 
of  reality's  characters.  To  the  awakening  consciousness,  it  may  well 
have  been  the  earliest  datum,  even  though  then  meaning  hardly  more 
than  vague  shocks  or  bumps  and  the  distinction  of  them.  At  any 
rate,  many  separate  beings  are  presented — that  is  the  first  object 
upon  which  thought  can  exercise  itself.  But  we  are  not  now  con- 
cerned with  genetic  order;  rather  with  the  objective  and  primarily 
the  material  world.  Early  man  was  doubtless  more  aware  of  such  a 
datum  at  night;  for  at  night  he  had  opportunity  to  contemplate, 
and  he  saw  the  manifold  of  lights  arranged  in  the  heavens.  But  by 
day  the  same  couple  was  offered  to  him  by  impinging  objects,  by 
the  resistance  or  non-resistance  of  the  environment.  Nor  have  we 
of  to-day  been  able  to  do  without  these  categories,  though  reflection 
has  taught  us  to  call  them,  in  the  conceptual  domain,  term  and 
relation,  and  in  the  physical  universe,  real  substantial  things  or 
material  objects  and  their  arrangements.  For  the  category  of  sub- 
stance is  embedded  in  this  category  of  real  things;  objects  in  the 
external  world  come  to  us  as  real  in  and  for  themselves,  present 
actualities  with  a  subsistence  of  their  own  here  and  now,  no  matter 
what  may  appear  at  some  later  time.  We  may  have  to  revise  our 
interpretation  of  them,  but  the  revision  must  be  fair  to  the  present 
appearance;  this  appearance  has  a  natural  right,  as  every 
man  has  a  natural  right  to  live.  It  may  turn  out  to 
be  illusory — so  we  later  learn — but  illusions  have  objective 
grounds.  There  is  something  out  there;  there  are  many 
somethings,  indeed,  and  they  are  in  some  sort  of  order.  They  have  a 


THE  DICHOTOMY  OF  NATURE  367 

solidity  and  a  fastness  which  we  designate  by  the  word  substance. 
Substance  connotes  that  self-sufficiency  and  stability  which  is  the 
essence  of  being.  Man's  primary  discovery  is  that  there  are  sub- 
stances or  beings  and  that  they  have  relations.  These  two  are  the 
fixed  hooks  on  which  all  subsequent  information  is  hung;  meta- 
physics starts  from  them  and  returns  to  them. 

Of  this  primitive  and  ultimate  pair,  the  first  was  more  emphasized 
in  olden  time,  while  the  second  is  having  its  turn  to-day,  and  some- 
what to  the  exclusion  of  its  mate.  The  turn  came  to  self-conscious- 
ness in  E.  Cassirer's  Substanz-theorie  und  Funktwns-theorie;  but 
that  side  of  the  wheel  has  been  long  in  view.  Modern  philosophy 
began  with  the  two  Cartesian  substances,  but  matter  at  once  evapo- 
rated into  space,  and  mind  was  hardly  more  than  thoughts.  With 
Spinoza,  substance  retired  into  the  infinite  distance;  in  Leibniz,  it 
was  replaced  by  force.  If  Locke  still  dallied  with  common  sense, 
Hume  offended  it  beyond  possible  reconciliation  by  his  reduction 
of  matter  to  its  effect  upon  mind,  and  of  mind  to  a  series  of  ideas. 
For  some  centuries  now,  mathematics  has  been  the  philosophic  ideal, 
and  mathematics  knows  no  substance.  To-day,  the  mathematical  ap- 
proach to  the  philosophy  of  nature  has  usurped  the  place  of  favor, 
and  none  may  enter  the  field  who  can  not  say  much  in  symbolic  form. 
But  even  among  the  non-mathematical,  is  not  the  relational  bias  evi- 
dent? The  pragmatic  tendency  is  to  define  things  by  their  con- 
sequences, to  interpret  all  by  the  context,  to  deny  self-sufficiency 
everywhere.  The  Bergsonian  system  views  the  temporal  relation  as 
the  very  stuff  of  life.  The  speculative  idealist  finds  the  pathway 
to  reality  in  the  interdependence  of  all  things,  rather  than  in  the 
things  themselves;  finite  personality,  soul-substance,  and  material 
stuff  live  only  in  their  mutual  connections  and  relations.  And  is 
it  not  the  relations  between  men,  rather  than  the  individual  man, 
that  command  our  attention  in  what  is  called  the  "social  problem"! 
We  no  longer  think  of  the  individual  as  a  character  existing  in  and 
for  himself,  but  as  one  having  his  whole  being  in  the  relations  he 
bears  towards  his  fellows.  Our  modern  philosophy  and  our  modern 
way  of  thought,  whether  monism,  or  pragmatism,  or  intuitionism,  is 
always  relationism. 

But  a  relation  without  terms  is  meaningless;  and  a  philosophy 
which  has  forgotten  the  category  of  substance  can  not,  in  the  end, 
give  an  intelligent  account  of  reality.  However  refined  its  analyses, 
however  imposing  its  array  of  proofs  and  its  logical  technique,  it 
becomes  no  more  than  a  science  of  the  possible,  a  formalism  dis- 
sociated from  the  real  world.  In  spite  of  our  respect  for  their  logical 
attainments,  it  is  hard  for  us  to  repress  the  feeling  that  the  work 


368  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  Messrs.  Russell,  Whitehead,  Broad  and  Alexander  commits  the  old 
fallacy  of  deriving  the  individual  from  the  universal,  real  things  from 
their  connections,  matter  from  the  union  of  space  and  time,  terms 
from  their  relations.  We  suspect  that  under  these  leaders  philosophy 
is  in  danger  of  becoming  a  sophisticated  cult,  and  that  we  must  go 
about  on  the  other  tack,  paying  respect  to  the  empirical  deliver- 
ances of  science,  to  the  kinds  of  substance  it  shows  us,  to  the  structure 
of  the  atom,  the  constitution  of  the  cell,  and  the  order  of  the  sidereal 
system.  For  science  deals  first  and  last  with  real  and  separate  things, 
with  electrons  which  have  permanent  volumes,  and  mechanical  masses 
that  resist  impact.  If  some  of  these  were  destroyed,  presumably 
the  others  would  remain ;  even  though  their  behavior  might  be 
altered,  their  reality  would  be  undiminished,  and  thereby  their  sub- 
stantiality vindicated.  Philosophy,  after  all,  can  not  afford  to  cut 
itself  quite  loose  from  common  sense.  Common  sense  is  not  a  suffi- 
cient condition  of  philosophy,  but  it  is  a  necessary  one.  The  states- 
man, however  far-seeing  his  vision,  can  not  well  neglect  public  opin- 
ion, though  public  opinion  is  far  from  being  a  sufficient  guide ;  and 
philosophy,  likewise,  must  defer  to  the  common  belief  in  substances. 
Herein  we  have  something  to  learn  from  the  scholastics,  who  were 
able  to  combine  extreme  nicety  of  definition  with  regard  for  the 
categories  of  the  practical  man — these  being  the  categories  of  com- 
mon sense.  We  must  frankly  acknowledge  that  not  even  the  most  im- 
pressive massing  of  scientific  technicalities,  or  the  most  brilliant 
literary  style,  can  make  motion  without  things  that  move,  or  time 
without  things  that  change,  any  less  meaningless  than  they  ever  were. 
Indeed,  the  modern  preference  for  relation  over  substance  would 
hardly  have  become  so  influential,  were  it  not  for  our  dislike  of  any- 
thing hidden.  We  wish  all  reality  to  be  laid  out  in  the  open,  in  this 
age  of  publicity;  whereas  a  substance  is  full  of  potencies  not  yet 
revealed,  and  contains  reserves  and  private  property  not  sharable. 
But  here,  too,  we  take  leave  alike  of  common  sense  and  of  scientific 
practise,  since  we  have  to  admit  the  hidden  and  latent  in  persons, 
and  since  science  can  not  do  without  potential  energy. 

Substances  and  relations  are  themselves  given  as  many.  In  fact, 
each  of  these  two  is  found  to  contain  a  dichotomy ;  for  each  contains 
two  chief  divisions,  and  each  of  these  again  two,  and  so  on.  This 
description,  we  shall  immediately  try  to  show,  holds  of  our  world 
as  now  presented  to  us;  but  also  it  may  be  sound  chronology.  It 
seems  not  unlikely  that  the  physical  universe  began  thus.  Scientists 
have  pictured  a  vague  nebula  with  lumps,  hardening  into  bodies  with 
empty  space  between  them,  and  eventually  providing  the  present 
manifold  universe.  Always,  to  be  sure,  there  were  substance  and 


THE  DICHOTOMY  OF  NATURE  369 

relations,  spatial  and  temporal,  as  well  as  some  degree  of  differentia- 
tion in  the  nebulous  mass.  A  quite  undifferentiated  unity  we  are  not 
asked  to  accept.  Being  must,  apparently,  have  started  (if  it  ever 
did  start)  with  something  of  the  duality  of  thing  and  relation.  But 
our  present  purpose  is  not  chronological ;  we  wish  rather  to  set  forth 
the  present  dichotomy  of  nature,  without  regard  to  its  genesis. 
And  we  find  it  to  be  of  the  following  Porphyroid  character,  which 
we  first  state  roughly  and  then  go  on  to  examine  in  more  detail. 
Relations  comprise  two  sorts,  space  and  time ;  space  comprises  quali- 
ties and  quantities.  Out  of  the  material  thus  provided  we  discover 
by  analysis,  identity  and  diversity,  individual  and  class,  ordinal  and 
cardinal  number,  intensive  and  extensive  quantity,  velocity  and  mass, 
and  endless  derivatives  of  these;  and  in  another  aspect,  act  and  po- 
tency, cause  and  chance.  These  categories  make  up  the  main  tale 
of  the  formal  side  of  the  world.  They  constitute  the  subject-matter 
(not,  properly  speaking,  the  object-matter)  of  science.  The  object- 
matter,  which  our  modern  philosophy  has  all  but  overlooked,  is  found 
in  the  dichotomy  of  the  other  initial  category,  thing  or  substance. 
Things  are  found  to  comprise  two  sorts,  living  and  non-living.  The 
latter  group  contains  mechanical  and  electrical  phenomena,  and  elec- 
trical phenomena  are  of  two  kinds,  positive  and  negative.  Living 
beings,  taken  en  masse,  are  either  plant  or  animal ;  plants  are  divided 
into  two  great  lines,  the  green  plants  and  the  bacteria,  while  animal 
evolution  culminates  in  the  two  main  divisions  of  arthropod  and 
vertebrate.  In  the  former  division,  as  Bergson  and  others  have 
pointed  out,  instinct  is  the  chief  guide  of  behavior;  in  the  latter, 
intelligence.  Herewith  we  are  introduced  to  the  fundamental  cleav- 
age of  mind  and  body,  and  a  long  chain  of  couples  in  the  region  of 
mind — fact  and  value,  theory  and  practise, .  art  and  science,  and  so 
on.  On  the  other  hand,  if  we  consider  the  individual  living  being, 
we  find  the  primary  distinction  within  the  cell,  of  nucleus  and  cyto- 
plasm; reproduction  by  the  process  of  bipartition;  and  early  in 
the  history  of  the  metazoa  and  metaphyta,  the  distinction  of  sex — 
a  distinction  which  in  the  highest  vertebrate  has  become  so  significant 
as  to  color  almost  the  whole  of  his  life.  Let  this  statement,  rough 
as  it  is,  and  even  inaccurate  in  certain  details,  suffice  as  an  indication 
of  our  plan. 

Now,  of  course,  the  universe  may  be  classified  from  many  points 
of  view ;  and  superficially  one  way  may  seem  as  good  as  another.  Yet 
on  the  whole,  the  dichotomic  plan  can  hardly  be  called  arbitrary. 
The  distinctions  are  in  many,  if  not  all,  cases  easy  and  objective; 
they  are  also  fundamental,  and  have  been  reached  or  confirmed  by 
centuries  of  scientific  inquiry.  Some  there  are  who  declare  that  the 


370  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

scheme  is  anthropomorphic,  due  perhaps  to  the  unsuspected  influence 
of  man's  bilateral  symmetry,  or  even  his  interest  in  sex;  but  it  is 
not  likely  that  the  distinction  between  positive  and  negative  electric- 
ity, or  between  time  and  space,  or  animals  and  plants,  or  nucleus  and 
cytoplasm,  has  such  an  origin.  Nothing  is  more  objective  than  these ; 
they  are  clearly  distinct  and  they  clearly  belong  together.  It  may 
be  that  the  couples  in  the  field  of  mind — art  and  science,  value  and 
fact,  good  and  bad,  etc. — have  a  subjective  source  in  man's  bilateral 
symmetry ;  even  so,  this  symmetry  is  a  physical  fact,  common  to  vast 
numbers  of  organisms  and  deserving  a  place  with  other  fundamental 
dualities.  We  propose,  then,  to  follow  the  clew,  studying  in  turn 
the  couples  above  named,  and  their  logical  relations  in  structure  and 
function. 

And  first,  how  are  substance  and  relation  related  ?  In  three  ways : 
they  are  complementary,  i.e.,  they  hang  together  in  a  certain  way, 
they  are  opposites,  and  they  form  an  asymmetrical  pair. 

Substance  means  a  solid  real  thing  which  impresses  us;  of  the 
senses,  it  is  most  clearly  given  to  touch.  Touch  is,  of  all  our  experi- 
ences, the  special  witness  of  reality,  as  when  we  test  an  hallucination 
by  prodding  it.  The  scientist,  treating  inertia  as  matter's  funda- 
mental attribute,  takes  his  cue  from  touch,  since  touch  is  the  sense 
of  resistance,  which  is  all  that  inertia  means.  But  form  and  arrange- 
ment, while  real  enough,  are  more  subject  to  illusion  and  less  authori- 
tative in  their  own  right.  Eye  and  ear,  the  organs  devoted  to  these 
categories,  are  not  the  last  court  of  appeal  like  touch,  and  correspond- 
ingly, substance  has  more  of  reality  about  it  than  relation.  Sub- 
stance is  in  this  manner  prior  to  form.  If  neither  has  much  meaning 
without  the  other,  that  fact  is  not  true  of  each  in  the  same  sense  or 
degree.  While  we  know  no  substance,  perhaps,  that  is  not  in  a  mani- 
fold, such  a  thing  is  conceivable.  We  may  imagine  one  bright  star 
in  a  dark  space  as  the  sole  content  of  the  visual  field ;  a  term  with 
almost  no  relation,  or  with  relation  only  of  distinction  from  the 
nothingness  about  it.  But  we  can  hardly  conceive  a  relation  without 
terms :  that,  indeed,  seems,  as  noted  above,  a  true  case  of  what  ideal- 
ists call  a  vicious  abstraction.  If,  then,  relation  and  terms  hang  to- 
gether, the  latter  do  more  of  the  supporting;  and  the  mistake  of 
idealists  has  been  to  be  so  prepossessed  with  the  connection  of  these 
as  to  overlook  their  difference.  The  relation  between  them  is  not 
the  same  in  its  two  directions;  they  are  an  asymmetrical  couple. 
And  we  might  have  seen  this  by  analysis,  also.  Relation  is  but  carry- 
ing away  from  the  present  real  thing  to  another,  and  you  can  not 
carry  without  a  burden;  which  burden  here  is  being.  But  thing  or 
substance  is,  as  immediate  experience,  to  a  degree  self-contained,  and 


THE  DICHOTOMY  OF  NATURE  371 

needs  nothing  to  support  it.  Thus,  relations  need  terms,  and  imply 
them,  while  a  term  makes  relation  possible  but  does  not  absolutely 
imply  it.  "We  may  add  that  the  notion  of  a  relationless  term  has 
hovered  over  the  philosophic  arena  ever  since  Parmenides;  notably 
in  the  Thomistic  God  and  the  idealistic  Absolute,  to  say  nothing  in 
detail  of  the  mystics. 

But  the  two  prime  categories  are  also  opposites.  Relation,  in 
the  most  general  meaning,  is  opposed  to  thing,  because  it  carries  us 
away  to  another,  as  motion  is  the  opposite  of  rest.  But  it  is  not 
opposed  in  the  contradictory  way ;  this  transition  is  not  a  denial  but 
an  ignoring.  It  is  like  attention,  which,  selecting  one  and  rejecting 
another,  negates  without  denying  that  other;  there  is  no  contra- 
diction in  the  process.  Indeed,  to  negate  one  thing  without  denying 
it,  is  to  present  another.  Otherness  is  the  original  of  negation,  while 
contradiction  is  negation  perverted  and  sinful.  And  so  relation  is 
that  sort  of  negation  which  does  not  transgress  the  law  of  contradic- 
tion. If  a  substantial  thing  is  position  without  contradiction,  rela- 
tion is  opposition  without  contradiction. 

Thus  far,  then,  we  have  substance  and  relation,  and  the  connec- 
tion between  them,  which  is  that  (1)  they  hang  together  in  a  rather 
free  way,  (2)  one  is  prior  to  the  other,  and  (3)  they  are  non-con- 
tradictory opposites. 

The  second  member,  relation,  is  a  very  vague  affair.  As  man 
becomes  acquainted  with  his  external  world,  two  kinds  of  relation 
disengage  themselves ;  relations  of  co-existence  and  sequence.  These 
are  given  to  sense,  though  not  to  the  same  sense.  Space  is  given 
chiefly  to  vision,  as  substance  to  touch,  and  time  preeminently  to 
hearing.  For  vision  is  not  directly,  though  it  is  indirectly,  of  bodies 
or  resisting  things;  touch  has  spatial  qualities,  as  bodies  are  in 
space,  but  vision  is  concerned  primarily  with  extended  things. 
Touch  is  also,  in  a  way,  intenser  than  vision,  as  substance  is  more 
real  than  relation.  Vision,  even  of  the  most  violent  sort,  as  of  the 
sun,  does  not  shock  the  organism  to  the  degree  of  the  gentlest  blow. 
It  is  impossible  to  see  objects  without  seeing  them  extended  or  seeing 
some  distance  between  them.  And  though  we  see  processes  and 
thereby  time,  we  may  also  see  a  still  panorama,  which,  for  a  few 
seconds  at  least,  gives  to  vision  no  inkling  of  temporal  quality.  Hear- 
ing, however,  is  never  without  that  quality ;  as  it  gives  no  spread-out 
content  which  so  absorbs  attention  as  to  exclude  the  awareness  of 
change.  There  is  more  discreteness  in  hearing  than  in  vision,  and 
discreteness,  as  we  shall  see,  is  a  peculiarity  of  time.  We  are  here 
talking  of  objective  space  and  time  which  science  uses,  mathematics 
analyzes,  and  man  more  or  less  perfectly  apprehends  in  vision  and 


372  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOI'Il  Y 

hearing.  We  neglect  the  distinctions  between  conceptual,  percep- 
tual, visual  and  tactual  space,  and  between  perceived,  remembered 
and  scientific  time. 

Space  and  time  hang  together.  Most  of  the  real  things  in  our 
material  world  are  in  motion;  substances  occupy  space  and  change 
their  occupation  in  time.  So  we  are  accustomed  to  say  that  each 
category  involves  the  other.  But  if  no  more  be  said,  the  account  is 
misleading.  They  involve  each  other  in  different  ways,  and  the  im- 
plication is  not  always  binding  in  the  same  degree.  Time  might  occur 
in  a  single  substance — as  if  a  star,  with  no  fellows,  might  go  through 
a  change  of  color.  Space  is  here  involved,  yet  not  in  the  sense  of  a 
positive  condition  with  properties  of  its  own — positions,  distances, 
etc.  Various  real  things  must  be  given  to  afford  such  space;  and 
time  alone,  of  itself,  does  not  imply  such  variety  of  coexistence. 
Time  no  more  involves  coexistence  than  one  real  thing  involves 
others.  Thereby  time  is  more  like  its  father,  substance,  whereas 
space  will  be  seen  more  to  resemble  its  mother,  relation.  There  is  a 
certain  possibility  of  independence  about  time;  though  this  is  not 
actual,  for  really  the  world  is  a  manifold.  That  being  so,  we  find 
the  two  interwoven.  Yet  there  is  a  difference ;  time  is  nothing  with- 
out events  or  change,  as  a  relation  is  nothing  without  terms;  and 
therefore  there  is  no  empty  time.  Time  is  relative  to  events,  or  con- 
tents, and  must,  in  the  end,  be  estimated  by  the  number  of  events 
that  occur.  Eventless  or  empty  time  is  a  paradox,  and  time  there- 
fore actually  is  interpenetrated  by  things;  whereas  empty  space,  or 
space  without  time,  seems  not  so  absurd.  There  may  be  empty 
volumes;  there  may  be  no  ether.  In  fact,  if  there  is  no  ether,  prob- 
ably most  of  space  is  empty;  the  distances  between  atoms  are  far 
greater  than  the  extent  of  each  atom,  and  there  may  be  places 
through  which  electrons  never  actually  pass.  There  may  also  be, 
beyond  the  Milky  Way,  an  infinite  volume  of  empty  space  in  every 
direction.  But  is  not  empty  space  then  a  relation  without  terms? 
Rather  it  is  the  nearest  approach  we  find  in  nature,  to  a  relation  with- 
out terms.  It  is  not  quite  without  its  relata,  but  these  relata  are  not 
in  the  first  instance  things,  but  positions.  Now  a  position  is  not  de- 
finable without  reference  to  a  body;  it  is  given  to  sense  as  occupied 
by  a  body,  and  to  thought  as  capable  of  occupation  even  when  not 
occupied.  So  space,  which  is  made  of  positions,  is  relative  to  body, 
though  not  always  to  actual  bodies.  But  it  is  relative  in  a  peculiar 
way,  which  shows  us  that  even  relations  may  have  a  semi-substan- 
tial character.  Spatial  relations  are  presented  directly;  we  see  the 
stretch  between  two  bodies  and  the  area  of  a  body;  we  even  see 
pure  positions  without  magnitude.  Relations  are  as  much  data  as 


THE  DICHOTOMY  OF  NATURE  373 

things  or  qualities;  and  so  are  points.  In  the  matter  of  points  we 
have  been  enslaved  by  mathematism,  which  declares  them  to  be  the 
result  of  analysis,  the  limit  of  a  series.  But  we  should  never  get  the 
notion  of  that  limit  from  the  series  itself,  as  it  is  beyond  the  series; 
all  limits  are  independent  of  their  series  and  must  be  given  directly 
and  independently,  to  be  known.  Points,  however,  are  given  to 
experience  when  we  see  a  minimum  visibile  which  appears  to  have 
no  extension.  That  the  physical  object  thus  seen  turns  out  to  be 
fairly  large  does  not  alter  the  character  of  our  sight  of  the  object. 
We  know  just  how  a  true  point  would  look  if  we  could  see  it,  as  we 
know  by  a  photograph  just  how  a  certain  man  would  look  if  we 
could  see  him.  A  point  is  not  merely  a  conceptual  limit  but  a 
sense-datum,  though  revealed  to  us  in  an  illusion.  The  same  is  true 
of  a  straight  line.  We  see  what  looks  like  a  line  and  straight,  and 
were  it  not  for  that  datum  we  should  never  frame  the  notion  of  a 
line  as  the  limit  of  a  narrowing  plane.  All  these  spatial  entities 
are  given  in  one  way  or  another,  though  given  as  potencies  or  capa- 
cities, while  yet  real.  Space  could  not  wholly  break  away  from  mat- 
ter or  things,  but  it  comes  just  as  near  as  it  can  to  that  condition ; 
empty  space  is  the  image  of  presented  nothingness ;  the  way  nothing- 
ness would  look  if  we  could  see  it.  Thereby,  it  is  wrong  to  derive  the 
concept  of  nothing  from  not- this,  not-that,  and  so  on  to  the  limit ;  for 
we  could  have  no  notion  of  the  limit  were  it  not  in  some  fashion 
given  to  sense.  Yet  even  here  space  is  relative,  though  only  in 
the  last  analysis;  relative  to  bodies,  by  which  it  is  the  capacity  of 
being  occupied.  And  this  capacity  means  that  something  may  move 
in — which  in  turn  involves  time.  Thus  it  is  impossible  to  describe 
space  without  at  least  eventual  reference  to  time,  whereas  time  may 
be  described  without  reference  to  space  though  in  fact  the  two  are 
mingled.  Time  and  space  are  tied  together,  but  not  glued  together ; 
and  the  cord  is  very  elastic,  for  space  can  recede  to  an  indefinite  re- 
move from  time.  Moreover,  though  the  cord  is  made  fast  to  the 
inwards  of  space,  it  is  affixed  to  time  only  on  the  surface.  Space 
implies  time  more  than  time  implies  space,  while  also  space  can  roam 
free  to  an  almost  unbounded  extent. 

When  philosophers  declare  that  space  and  time  are  thoroughly 
interpenetrated,  they  seem  to  be  unduly  swayed  by  the  modern  love 
of  connectedness,  and  the  correlative  hatred  of  the  dissociated  and 
solitary. 

It  has  scarcely  been  recognized  that  time  is  the  opposite  of  space ; 
opposite  as  motion  and  rest  are  opposite.  Time  means  change,  which 
is  both  destruction  and  creation ;  space  can  not  be  destroyed,  nor  can 
new  space  arise,  however  far  space  be  penetrated  by  time.  Time 
can  not  be  empty ;  space  can  be  and  as  regards  gross  matter  must  be, 


374  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

to  allow  motion.  Space  thus,  by  its  negativity,  makes  room  for  time, 
which  is  full,  to  pass.  Time  also  is  impossible  without  differentia- 
tion, being  succession  of  events,  of  which  the  present  exceeds  the 
others  in  actuality ;  space,  being  a  potency,  and  by  itself,  empty,  is 
everywhere  the  same,  and  as  homogeneous  as  pure  nothingness. 
Even  if  we  supposed  that  space  grew  smaller  as  we  receded  from  a 
given  spot,  that  would  be  rather  a  body  growing  smaller;  for  if 
space  were  smaller,  we  need  only  draw  upon  the  surroundings  to 
make  it  larger.  If  a  straight  line  be  supposed  to  have  curvature, 
we  need  only  swerve  from  that  line  in  a  direction  opposite  that  of 
the  curvature,  to  find  the  true  straight  line.  Homogeneity  is  no 
postulate  or  convention,  but  a  deliverance  of  experience,  or  a  con- 
sequence thereof ;  for  whatever  variations  are  displayed  may  be  com- 
pensated from  the  surrounding  void.  Again,  time  is  a  device  for 
securing  a  manifold  without  many  things ;  an  accomplishment  which 
space  can  not  compass.  Space  on  the  other  hand  makes  up  for  the 
destructive  affect  of  time  by  its  power  of  coexistence ;  thereby  some- 
thing permanent  persists  along  with,  or  underneath,  the  series  of 
changes,  and  the  integrity  of  substance  is  preserved  through  change. 
Time  is  irreversible  and  space  is  symmetrical;  which  explains  why 
we  experience  only  a  little  jot  of  time,  the  small  specious  present, 
while  we  can  see  nearly  one  half  of  infinite  space.  Moreover,  to  take 
for  granted  some  of  the  later  categories,  we  can  see  a  whole  series 
of  complementary  terms  connected  with  these  two  respectively. 
In  time,  history  is  alone  possible,  with  its  progress  or  retrogression ; 
also  purpose  and  causation,  which  are  the  roots  of  value,  responsi- 
bility and  other  categories  of  personality.  Space,  on  the  other 
hand,  gives  us  the  type  of  a  fixed,  ordered  universe,  such  as  rational- 
ists and  systematists  love.  It  is  the  inspiration  of  the  pantheist 
Spinoza,  who  wrote  ordine  geometrico,  and  of  absolute  idealism, 
which  depreciates  time.  The  latter  is  the  guide  of  monadists  or 
personalists ;  of  a  practical  philosophy  like  Thomism,  whose  central 
category  is  causation.  In  fact  the  whole  cleavage  of  theory  and 
practise,  of  structure  and  function,  of  equality  and  privilege — the 
great  body  of  human  dualisms,  takes  its  origin  from  this  objec- 
tive source.  But  for  the  present  we  do  not  show  this  in  detail;  we 
concentrate  attention  on  a  distinction  which  is  fundamental  for 
later  insights,  viz.,  that  space  is  quantitative  and  time  is  not.  More 
exactly,  space  has  but  a  minimum  which  is  non-quantitative — the 
point — while  time  has  but  a  minimum  that  is  so— the  little  specious 
present;  and  even  this  varies  irresponsibly. 

The  reason  why  time  is  not  a  quantity  is  that  it  is  not  a  whole, 
for  the  parts  drop  out;  as  Baron  Munchausen 's  horse,  whose  rear 
•was  cut  away,  could  not  be  filled.  Scientists  often  speak  as  if  they 


THE  DICHOTOMY  OF  NATURE  375 

measured  time,  but  they  do  not  do  so  at  all ;  and  Professor  Bergson  is, 
we  think,  quite  right  in  saying  that  science,  and  philosophy  too, 
have  too  much  cast  reality  into  the  mould  of  space.  Science  really 
does  nothing  but  note  coincidences  between  different  events,  and 
predict  further  coincidences.  Whether  all  clocks  and  other  material 
processes  go  faster  in  one  day  and  slower  the  next,  or  as  is  gener- 
ally supposed,  at  a  uniform  rate  in  both,  is  quite  indifferent;  all 
that  calculation  and  prediction  require  is  that  the  processes  keep 
step.  If  the  clock 's  hand  goes  around  24  X  365 J  times  every  time 
the  earth  goes  around  the  sun,  that  is  enough  for  science.  If 
the  clocks,  accurately  made,  keep  time  with  one  another,  so  that 
each  angular  position  of  the  hands  in  one  corresponds  to  the  same 
in  another,  no  more  is  needed.  Science  aims  only  to  predict  that 
when  the  hands  are  in  a  certain  position,  a  certain  event  will  occur. 
When  a  pendulum  swings  back  and  forth  there  is  neither  inequality 
nor  equality  of  the  intervals.  If  they  feel  equal  or  unequal,  that  is 
perhaps  because  we  unconsciously  estimate  them  in  terms  of  bodily 
rhythms.  The  length  of  these  we  do  not  know,  nor  have  we  any  test 
of  their  uniformity.  The  feeling  of  equality  or  inequality  may,  in 
fact,  be  as  illusory  as  the  feeling  that  we  directly  see  a  distance.  Mr. 
Broad,  who  accepts  time-quantity,  argues  that  "it  is  very  unlikely 
that  the  rotation  of  the  earth,  the  swings  of  a  pendulum,  and  the 
vibrations  of  an  electron  are  all  retarded  according  to  the  same 
law."1  But  we  do  not  need  to  suppose  these  processes  retarded 
alike,  or  hastened  alike,  or  uniform.  We  simply  want  the  events  in 
them  to  correspond  point  for  point.  Difference  of  velocity  means 
different  amount  of  displacement  in  two  bodies  whose  motion  begins 
and  ceases  simultaneously.  The  displacement  may  be  actual  or 
potential.  If  body  A  has  at  one  instant  a  tendency  to  greater  dis- 
placement than  body  B  at  one  instant,  A  has  the  greater  velocity. 
Thus  velocity  may  be  defined  without  presumption  of  time-quantity. 
Time  deals  with  events,  not  quantities;  events  ordered  in  a  series 
where  each  has  a  definite  position  before,  or  after,  or  with,  some 
other.  Thus  order  does  not  imply  quantity,  though  it  may  cor- 
respond to  quantity;  while  quantity  no  doubt  does  imply  order  of 
less  and  greater,  even  as  space  implies  time.  To  be  sure,  we  say 
truthfully  that  a  day  is  longer  than  one  of  its  hours.  Yet  that 
could  not  be,  unless  a  day  signified  that  the  earth  had  gone  through 
more  space  by  the  24th  than  by  the  end  of  the  first  hour.  We  de- 
fine day  and  hour  by  reference  to  quantity  of  displacement,  and 
then  of  course  they  seem  quantitative.  But  in  a  non-spatial  world, 
where  a  substance  went  through  a  series  of  changes,  the  only  mean- 
i  Perception,  Physics,  and  Eeality,  p.  318. 


376  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ing  we  could  assign  to  time  would  be  the  number  of  changes  it  had 
suffered.  In  a  wholly  mental  world,  for  instance,  if  a  substance 
should  go  through  a  series  of  changes  and  then  return  identical  to 
its  original  state,  time  would  so  far  retreat  on  its  own  tracks  and 
the  past  would  be  revoked. 

In  space,  however,  there  is  true  quantity,  because  there  are 
wholes  whose  parts  stay  to  fill  them  up.  Nor  does  the  equality  of 
two  lengths  depend  upon  the  motion  of  a  measuring-rod,  super- 
posed on  each  in  turn  and  postulated  as  invariant.  To  compare  the 
lengths  of  two  straight  lines  A  and  B,  we  describe  a  sphere  with  A 
as  radius,  select  the  position  A'  of  that  radius  which  is  parallel  to 
B,  and  construct  a  parallelogram  whose  opposite  sides  are  A'  and 
B,  and  whose  base  is  the  line  joining  the  corresponding  ends  of  A' 
and  B.  If  then  the  upper  side  starting  from  the  other  end  of  A' 
cuts  line  B  exactly  at  its  other  end,  B  is  equal  to  A;  otherwise  it 
is  unequal  to  A.  Obviously  it  is  the  simultaneous  presence  of  the 
entities  concerned  which  renders  the  test  possible.  But  in  time  the 
backward  end  of  our  line  always  drops  out.  If  we  are  to  represent 
time  by  a  line,  it  will  not  be  by  a  straight  line,  which  has  a  fixed 
length.  The  line  will  have  any  curvature  we  wish;  it  may  even 
curve  back  into  its  beginning. 

Until  recently  it  was  believed  that  all  the  processes  of  nature 
do  keep  step.  So  the  defender  of  time-length  says  "whilst  it  is 
perfectly  possible  that  a  series  which  seems  isochronous  and  ful- 
fills the  conditions  with  respect  to  another  apparently  isochronous 
series  might  not  obey  them  when  tested  with  respect  to  another  ap- 
parently isochronous  series,  yet,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  this  does  not 
generally  happen."*  The  reason  all  the  processes  or  series  seem 
to  vary  together  is,  no  doubt,  that  they  are  of  about  the  same  order 
of  magnitude.  When  we  come  to  compare  very  high  velocities  with 
them,  we  find  that  the  two  orders  do  not  keep  step.  The  speed  of 
light  does  not,  like  other  speeds  we  are  conversant  with,  increase  as 
we  move  toward,  or  decrease  as  we  move  away  from,  the  light- 
source.  Now  if  uniform  velocity  meant  equal  space  in  equal  times, 
then  our  time  would  have  to  shorten  itself,  or  our  space  to  enlarge 
itself,  to  account  for  the  discrepancy ;  but  both  of  these  are  really 
absurd.  If,  however,  time  has  no  fixed  quantity,  there  is  no  reason 
why  a  series  of  changes  like  the  light-waves  should  always  give  the 
same  number  for  the  same  number  of  swings  of  the  clock's  pendu- 
lum. Keeping  step  between  pendulums  and  light-waves  is  a  phenom- 
enon which  can  not  be  predicted  or  expected  a  priori.  There  is 
nothing  paradoxical  in  its  absence.  The  only  paradox  lies  in  the 

*  O.  D.  Broad,  Perception,  Phytict  and  Reality,  p.  321. 


THE  DICHOTOMY  OF  NATURE  377 

interpretation;  in  time  being  itself  altered,  or  space  changed  in 
amount.  Indeed,  these  conceptions  refute  themselves;  for  if  time 
is  hurried  or  delayed,  there  is  a  standard  time  by  comparison  with 
which  the  change  is  to  be  detected,  and  this  standard  is  itself  un- 
altered. And  the  same  holds,  mutatis  mutandis,  of  space.  But 
while  we  have  very  good  empirical  reasons  for  predicating  quantity 
and  uniformity  of  space,  we  have  no  such  reasons  for  doing  the 
same  by  time.  So  much  on  the  topic  of  the  opposition  between 
space  and  time. 

If  substance  is  more  real  than  relation,  time  is  in  the  same  way 
more  real  than  space.  Time  lives  by  emphasis;  we  note  its  pas- 
sage by  rhythms,  which  impress  our  attention,  whereas  contempla- 
tion of  the  uniformity  of  space  tends  to  sleep,  as  when  we  gaze 
into  the  crystal.  So  beauty  of  sound,  or  music  which  is  given  to 
hearing  the  temporal  sense  moves  us  far  more  than  beauty  of  sight, 
as  of  color  or  form.  But  if  time  is  stronger  than  space,  space  is 
bigger  than  time.  Not  only  has  space  three  ways  of  extending,  but 
it  lies  there  a  vast  empty  potency,  offering  equal  opportunity  to 
all  material  possibilities,  and  exercising  no  restrictive  force.  Time 
does  not  actually  lie  out  before  us,  for  the  future  is  not  an  empty 
receptacle,  but  is  largely  predetermined  by  past  and  present.  Later 
we  shall  see  that  space  is  the  source  of  chance,  as  is  time  of  causa- 
tion; at  present  it  is  enough  to  say  that  they  are  related  somewhat 
as  act  and  potency.  In  consequence  of  their  asymmetry,  they  do 
not  look  opposite.  For  time  is,  to  our  spatialized  mode  of  thought, 
easily  symbolized  by  a  line,  and  a  line  does  not  appear  complemen- 
tary to  a  volume.  But  time  is  not  a  line,  in  which  the  elements 
coexist.  Extensive  quantity  does  not  characterize  it;  rather  we 
must  say  that  time  is  intensive.  If  the  present  is  big  with  the  fu- 
ture, the  bigness  is  a  density;  while  space  is  big,  not  with  any 
precise  future,  but  with  all  futures,  as  well  as  present  and  past — 
in  short,  space  is  big  irrespective  of  its  particular  contents,  big 
with  its  own  bigness.  And  in  fact,  all  the  comparisons  we  have 
made  between  time  and  space  show  the  asymmetry  of  their  relation- 
ship ;  none  more  so  indeed,  than  the  most  obvious  difference  of  all, 
that  time  itself  is  asymmetrical  while  space  is  perfectly  balanced  in 
all  directions. 

We  proceed  to  the  next  pair  of  categories.  As  relation  was 
found  to  comprise  space  and  time,  so  space  is  found  to  contain  two 
sorts  of  entity,  viz.,  qualities  and  quantities.  Quantities  are  directly 
sensed  in  the  very  perception  of  space;  qualities,  while  equally 
sensed,  are  given  in  connection  with  things  or  substances.  The 
empty  separation  or  stretch  between  two  stars  has  quantity;  the 


378  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

positions  of  the  stars  themselves  are  revealed  by  qualitative  distinc- 
tion of  light  from  darkness.  If  positions  are  compared  with 
lengths,  the  qualitative  terms  of  space,  those  terms  are  marked  out 
by  being  occupied;  and  it  is  the  qualities  of  things  that  occupy 
them.  Quantities  are  more  akin  to  pure  space,  while  qualities  in- 
herit more  the  traits  of  their  grandfather,  substance,  and  their 
father,  time.  Qualities  might,  indeed,  be  found  in  a  spaceless  time- 
world,  in  the  form  of  nodes  in  the  fortunes  of  a  single  substance; 
even  in  a  pure  space-world,  they  show  their  kinship  with  sub- 
stance by  inhering  in  the  diverse  substances  which  people  that 
world.  They  are  unique  and  simple,  with  the  uniqueness  of  the 
present  moment;  they  change,  as  positions  by  themselves  can  not 
do,  either  by  movement  or  by  gradation  of  degree.  They  are,  like 
substance,  self-contained,  leaving  no  intrinsic  reference  to  anything 
else;  as  a  blue  spot  in  the  darkness  contains  no  reference  to  red  or 
other  color,  and  is  only  blueness.  But  a  quantity  is  intrinsically 
all  quantities,  as  it  is  continuous  and  infinitely  divisible;  likewise 
it  is  relative  to  external  quantities,  being  limited  by  them.  Quan- 
tity is  continuous  because  it  is  derived  from  space,  which  is  in  all 
ways  homogeneous.  Qualities  on  the  other  hand  are  discrete,  no 
matter  how  finely  graded  be  the  transition  from  one  to  another. 
In  a  band  of  color  passing  from  pure  red  through  purple  to  pure 
blue,  there  is  a  definite  point  where  blue  enters  and  another  where 
red  departs.  But  a  geometric  line  has  no  such  points  marked  off, 
unless  cut  by  another  line  of  different  direction;  and  directions, 
like  positions,  imply  quality. 

From  the  above  it  is  easy  to  see  that  quality  and  quantity  form 
a  connected  and  asymmetrical  couple  of  opposites.  They  are  con- 
nected in  that  particular  quantities  are  marked  out  by  their  color 
or  brightness,  which  are  visual  qualities.  Thus  quantities  of  them- 
selves imply  the  presence  of  some  quality.  But  quality  is  not  so 
intimately  bound  with  quantity,  just  as  substance,  we  saw,  is  not 
so  intimately  bound  with  relation,  or  time  with  space.  Time  could 
occur  in  a  single  thing,  and  so  could  quality.  Most  qualities,  how- 
ever, are  quantitative,  having  degree  or  intensity;  this  is  due  to 
quantitative  properties  of  moving  particles,  such  as  velocity  of 
oscillation.  Yet  this  phenomenon  does  not  seem  essential  to  the 
very  being  of  a  quality;  all  colors  might  have  but  one  degree  of 
brightness  or  saturation,  all  sounds  the  same  loudness,  without 
ceasing  to  be  perceptible  or  significant.  Quantities,  however,  con- 
tain just  that  implication  and  necessary  connection  which  qualities 
lack;  they  continue  the  tradition  of  the  category  of  relation,  as 
qualities  continue  that  of  substance.  Quantity  is  the  region,  there- 


THE  DICHOTOMY  OF  NATURE  379 

fore,  of  calculation,  of  discovery  of  something  new  from  the  already 
given,  by  implication;  quality  is  a  resting-point  for  the  inquiring 
mind.  From  the  point  of  view  of  one  quality  in  space,  it  is  chance 
what  the  others  will  be.  Thus  in  the  space-world,  each  of  these  cate- 
gories affirms  what  the  other  omits.  And  their  asymmetry  is  seen 
also  in  this  same  matter  of  implication.  Quantity  is  a  fecund  at- 
tribute, an  abstract  relational  affair  rich  in  potentialities  for 
thought  because  poor  in  individuation.  Quality  has  more  of  ac- 
tuality, quantity  more  of  potency  in  the  scheme  of  the  material 
world. 

Before  tracing  out  further  the  categorical  pattern,  we  must 
notice  that  we  have  now  before  us  something  like  a  completed  first 
stage,  or  cycle.  The  third  pair  of  categories  is  a  union  of  the  first 
two  pairs,  and  thus  closes  the  circle.  Real  things  or  substances  in 
time  and  without  space  to  move  in,  must  possess  quality;  there  is 
no  other  way  in  which  change  could  be  accomplished  in  them. 
Quality  thereby  enables  substances  to  change;  it  is  the  link  which 
unites  them  with  time.  On  the  other  hand,  relations  between  things 
in  space,  where  there  is  no  time  and  no  motion,  are  fixed  distances, 
and  distance  is  a  quantity.  A  quantity  is  thus  a  relation  assuming 
the  objective  form  of  space ;  extensive  in  the  first  instance,  and  in- 
tensive when  applied  to  a  momentary  quality.  Our  first  six  cate- 
gories then  complete  a  circle ;  but  as  the  range  of  information  to  be 
acquired  in  this  six-fold  universe  is  far  wider  than  in  the  original 
two-fold  world,  we  had  better  use  the  spiral  as  our  figure.  The 
spiral  is  an  open  circle,  wherein  we  ever  return  to  the  original  real- 
ity with  a  greater  breadth  of  knowledge.  And  at  the  same  time  we 
have  unwittingly  added  a  seventh  category  to  our  list,  which  has 
no  mate ;  to  wit,  the  category  of  the  whole,  the  synthesis,  the  iden- 
tity through  difference  of  the  material  already  presented.  But  we 
would  emphasize  the  objectivity  of  the  process;  none  of  the  cate- 
gories, not  even  the  seventh,  are  devised  by  man.  They  are  dis- 
covered; man's  activity  is  only  that  of  directing  his  attention. 
Nor  are  the  later  categories  deduced  from  the  earlier;  they  are 
found  branching  from  them  in  the  epigenetic,  not  the  prefonnative 
way. 

That  a  natural  cycle  is  here  finished,  is  confirmed  when  we  re- 
flect that  all  the  categories  used  by  the  sciences  of  external  nature 
have  now  been  provided,  either  explicitly  or  implicitly.  To  give 
an  example  or  two :  the  atomic  theory  is  but  the  scheme  of  the 
heavenly  bodies  in  space,  transformed  to  suit  the  needs  of  micro- 
cosmic  explanation.  Like  the  stars,  the  ultimate  atoms  are  single 
or  in  clusters,  drifting,  streaming,  revolving ;  the  greatest  difference 


380  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

being  in  the  extreme  rapidity  of  atomic  movements  on  the  whole, 
as  compared  with  those  of  the  sidereal  system.  Again,  the  ele- 
mentary quantities  of  physical  science  are  said  to  be  length,  mass 
and  time.  If  one  account  is  correct  there  are  really  two,  length 
and  mass.  Of  these,  length  is  already  delivered,  while  mass  is  but 
quantity  of  matter,  that  is,  of  inertia.  The  prejudice  against 
"quantity  of  matter"  may  be  dismissed  along  with  the  dislike  of 
substance.  If  matter  is  everywhere  of  uniform  density,  then  mass 
is  correlated  with  volume  and  is  an  extensive  quantity.  If  density 
differs  from  atom  to  atom  of  equal  volume,  then  mass  is  an  inten- 
sive quantity. 

We  shall  not  here  trace  in  detail  the  discovery  of  further  cate- 
gories ;  we  confine  ourselves  to  indication  of  the  method  of  that  dis- 
covery. Man  has  two  faculties  used  for  the  purpose,  sense  and 
thought.  Indeed,  these  two  are  related  perhaps  as  the  members  of 
each  couple  above  are  related;  that  does  not  now  concern  us. 
Thought  scrutinizes  the  gifts  of  sense,  which  takes  its  material  di- 
rect from  nature — even  as  animals  feed  upon  the  stores  of  energy 
laid  up  in  green  plants,  which  draw  their  sustenance  direct  from 
the  environment.  In  scrutinizing,  thought  finds  a  thousand-fold 
more  than  sense  has  mentioned,  in  the  package  it  has  conveyed. 
Thought  works  also  in  two  ways,  by  analysis  and  by  synthesis.  In 
both  alike  its  activity  consists  in  the  fixing  of  attention  upon  the 
given;  but  in  the  former  the  model  of  the  substance-time-quality 
series  is  its  guide,  and  in  the  latter  the  model  of  the  relational  cate- 
gories. Analysis  observes  each  category  by  itself,  whether  it  be  a 
category  of  the  substantive  side  or  one  of  the  relational  side.  Syn- 
thesis observes  the  relations  between  categories,  whether  they  be  the 
categories  of  the  one  group  or  the  other.  Let  it  now  suffice  to  say 
that  by  these  two  methods  we  derive  the  remaining  concepts  used 
in  science,  such  as  identity  and  diversity,  unit  and  collection,  indi- 
vidual and  universal,  permanence  and  change,  discreteness  and  con- 
tinuity, ordinal  and  cardinal  number,  and  so  on.  There  is,  how- 
ever, one  pair  whose  nature  can  not  be  fully  understood  from  the 
study  of  these  formal  categories  alone.  Causation  and  chance  are 
categories  of  the  real  world — though  modern  philosophy,  unlike 
ancient  and  medissval,  has  a  curious  bias  against  chance — and  they 
seem  to  form  an  exception  to  the  statement  we  made,  that  we  had 
provided  all  the  logical  instruments  of  scientific  research.  They 
serve  indeed  to  remind  us  that  our  world  is  not  a  merely  formal 
affair,  but  a  substantial  one  also.  Modern  philosophy,  indeed,  for- 
malistic  as  it  is,  does  tend  to  deny  causation  as  well  as  chance ;  that 
is,  as  we  hope  later  to  show,  because  it  has  lost  the  category  of 


THE  LENGTH  OF  HUMAN  INFANCY  381 

substance.  In  order  to  understand  causation  and  chance,  we  must 
betake  ourselves  to  that  side  of  nature's  dichotomy  which  is  re- 
vealed under  the  head  of  substances.  We  must  study  the  different 
kinds  of  real  things,  and  their  relations  to  one  another;  the  nature 
of  the  distinction  between  living  and  non-living,  mind  and  body, 
animal  and  plant,  green  plant  and  bacterium,  and  so  on. 

W.  H.  SHELDON. 
YALE  UNIVERSITY. 


THE  LENGTH  OF  HUMAN  INFANCY  IN  EIGHTEENTH- 
CENTURY  THOUGHT 

T  N  a  recent  number  of  this  JOURNAL*  Professor  W.  R.  Wells 
points  out  an  historical  anticipation  of  the  late  John  Fiske's 
"theory  regarding  the  meaning  and  value  of  the  prolonged  period 
of  human  infancy  in  comparison  with  the  briefer  infancy  of  lower 
animals."  Fiske  called  attention  to  the  fact  that,  in  Professor 
Wells 's  words,  "a  long  period  of  infancy  is  valuable,  first  in  giving 
time  for  educative  influences  to  work  upon  the  plastic  brain  and  in 
making  possible  thereby  a  higher  development  of  the  mind,  and 
second,  in  making  necessary  a  greater  degree  of  parental  coopera- 
tion than  is  the  case  among  the  lower  animals" — thus  resulting  in 
"the  development  of  the  domestic  virtues."  These  considerations 
seemed  to  Fiske  at  once  to  "bridge  the  gap  between  brute  and 
man,"  to  "account  for  the  evolution  of  human  intelligence  and 
morals,"  and  to  aid  in  "justifying  the  ways  of  God  to  man." 
But,  as  Professor  Wells  notes,  the  same  considerations  had  been 
dwelt  upon — especially  with  the  third  of  these  purposes  in  view — 
by  an  anonymous  writer  in  The  Friends'  Annual  in  1834. 

There  is,  however,  nothing  surprising  or  "striking"  about  this 
anticipation  of  Fiske ;  for  precisely  the  same  observations  concerning 
the  significance  of  the  longer  infancy  of  the  human  animal  were 
among  the  familiar  commonplaces  of  eighteenth-century  thought. 
They  were  expressed  both  in  the  philosophical  poem  and  in  the 
political  treatise  most  widely  read  in  that  century. 

In  his  account  of  the  beginning  and  early  stages  of  human  so- 
ciety, in  the  Essay  on  Man  (1733),  Pope  wrote  (Epistle  III,  125 
ft): 

Thus  bird  and  beast  their  common  charge  attend, 
The  mothers  nurse  it  and  the  sires  defend; 
The  young  dismissed  to  wander  earth  or  air, 
There  stops  the  instinct  and  there  ends  the  care.  .  .  . 
A  longer   care   man's   helpless   kind   demands; 

i  Vol.  XIX,  p.  208. 


382  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


That  longer  care  contract*  more  lasting  bands  .  .  . 

Still  as  one  brood,  and  as  another  rose, 

These  natural  love  maintained,  habitual  those.? 

The  last  scarce  ripened  into  perfect  man 

Saw  helpless  him  from  whom  their  life  began,  etc. 

Pope  thus  plainly  points  to  the  greater  length  of  human  infancy 
as  the  cause  of  the  development  of  the  family  relation  and  of  the 
domestic  virtues;  and  he  does  so  as  a  part  of  the  argument  of  a 
poem  of  which  the  professed  object  is  "to  vindicate  the  ways  of 
God  to  man. ' ' 

The  Essay  is  in  great  part  a  versification  of  passages  of  Boling- 
broke's  Fragments  or  Minutes  of  Essays,  which  appear  to  have  been 
written  for  the  purpose  of  thus  providing  the  poet  with  material. 
But  Pope  here  sees  the  point  better  than  his  philosophical  mentor. 
Bolingbroke  was  attempting,  on  the  one  hand,  to  show  that  ' '  man  is 
connected  by  his  nature  .  .  .  with  the  whole  tribe  of  animals,  and 
so  closely  with  some  of  them,  that  the  distance  between  his  intellec- 
tual faculties  and  theirs,  which  constitutes  as  really,  though  not  so 
sensibly,  as  figure  the  difference  of  species,  appears,  in  many  in- 
stances, small,  and  would  probably  appear  still  less,  if  we  had  the 
means  of  knowing  their  motives,  as  we  have  of  observing  their  ac- 
tions. ' ' 8  On  the  other  hand,  he  is  replying  to  those  theologians 
who  loved  to  dilate  upon  the  miseries  of  the  ' '  natural  state  of  man- 
kind." He  writes  accordingly: 

I  say  then,  that  if  men  come  helpless  into  the  world  like  other  animals ; 
if  they  require  even  longer  than  other  animals  to  be  nursed  and  edu- 
cated by  the  tender  instinct  of  their  parents,  and  if  they  are  able  much 
later  to  provide  for  themselves,  it  is  because  they  have  more  to  learn  and 
more  to  do;  it  is  because  they  are  prepared  for  a  more  improved  state 
and  for  greater  happiness.  .  .  .  The  condition  wherein  we  are  born  and 
bred,  the  very  condition  so  much  complained  of,  prepares  us  for  this  coinci- 
dence (of  social  and  self-love).  ...  As  our  parents  loved  themselves  in  us, 
so  we  love  ourselves  in  our  children,  and  in  those  to  whom  we  are  most 
nearly  related  by  blood.  Thus  far  instinct  improves  self-love.  Reason 
improves  it  further.4 

Bolingbroke  here  emphasizes  the  value  of  a  long  infancy  "in 
giving  time  for  educative  influences  to  work  upon  the  plastic 

*  Cf.   these   two   lines    with    Fiske  's    Outlines   of   Cosmic   Philosophy,   IV, 
134:     "When  at  last  the  association  is  so  long  kept  up  that  the  older  children 
are  growing  mature,  while  the  younger  ones  still  need  protection,  the  family 
relations  begin  to  become  permanent." 

•  "Fragment  L,"   Works,  1809,  ed.;   VIII,  p.  231. 

«"  Fragment  L"  op.  cit.,  p.  240.  Pope  versifies  the  last  four  sentences 
cited  in  Essay  on  Man,  Ep.  Ill,  lines  149,  124,  133-4. 


THE  LENGTH  OF  HUMAN  INFANCY       383 

brain,"  but  he  suggests  less  plainly  than  Pope  a  relation  between 
this  physiological  peculiarity  of  the  human  species  and  the  origin  of 
society. 

There  is  in  this,  however,  no  evidence  of  originality  on  Pope's 
part ;  for  the  more  significant  aspect  of  the  matter  had  been  pointed 
out  nearly  half  a  century  earlier  by  Locke,  in  Sections  79-80  of  the 
Second  Treatise  of  Government: 

The  end  of  conjunction  between  male  and  female  being  not  barely 
procreation,  but  the  continuation  of  the  species,  this  conjunction  betwixt 
male  and  female  ought  to  last,  even  after  procreation,  so  long  as  is  neces- 
sary to  the  nourishment  and  support  of  the  young  ones,  who  are  to  be 
sustained  by  those  that  got  them  until  they  are  able  to  shift  and  provide 
for  themselves.  .  .  .  And  herein,  I  think,  lies  the  chief,  if  not  the  only 
reason,  why  the  male  and  female  in  mankind  are  tied  to  a  longer  con- 
junction than  other  creatures,  viz.,  because  the  female  is  capable  of 
conceiving,  and,  de  facto,  is  commonly  with  child  again,  and  brings  forth 
too  a  new  birth,  long  before  the  former  is  out  of  a  dependency  for 
support  upon  his  parents'  help.  .  .  .  (Thus)  the  father  is  under  an  obliga- 
tion to  continue  in  conjugal  society  with  the  same  woman  longer  than 
other  creatures,  whose  young,  being  able  to  subsist  of  themselves  before 
the  time  of  procreation  returns  again,  the  conjugal  bond  dissolves 
itself.  .  .  .  Wherein  one  can  not  but  admire  the  wisdom  of  the  great 
Creator  who  .  .  .  hath  made  it  necessary  that  society  of  man  and  wife 
should  be  more  lasting  than  that  of  male  and  female  among  other  creatures, 
that  so  their  industry  might  be  encouraged,  and  their  interest  better 
united,  to  make  provision  and  lay  up  goods  for  their  common  issue. 

How  far  beyond  Locke  the  same  idea  can  be  tra.ced  I  do  not 
know,  but  it  is  certain  that  the  "theory  regarding  the  value  of 
infancy"  which  Fiske  presented  in  1874  as  something  "entirely 
new  in  all  its  features"5  had  been  clearly  set  forth  as  early  as 
1689,  in  one  of  the  most  familiar  classics  of  English  political  phi- 
losophy. 

Moreover,  neither  Mr.  Fiske  nor  his  Quaker  precursor  seem  to 
have  noted  that  their  theory  had  been  subjected  to  some  rather 
damaging  criticism  by  Rousseau  in  1755,  in  a  note  appended  to  his 
Discourse  on  the  Origin  of  Inequality.  Referring  to  the  passage 
of  Locke  cited  above,  Rousseau  remarks,  in  substance,  that,  if  it  is 
a  question  of  explaining  the  origin  of  the  family,  the  thing  pri- 
marily to  be  accounted  for  is  the  beginning  of  the  permanent  co- 
habitation of  male  and  female  during  the  nine  months  between 
copulation  and  the  birth  of  the  child.  If  the  parents  did  not  live 
together — i.e.,  if  the  habit  of  family  life  had  not  already  been 
formed — during  this  period,  why  should  the  primitive  human  male 
have  come  to  the  aid  of  the  female  " after  the  accouchement "f  "Why 

5  Outlines  of  Cosmic  Philosophy,  I,  p.  viii. 


384  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

should  he  aid  her  to  rear  an  infant  which  he  does  not  even  know 
to  be  his,  and  the  birth  of  which  he  has  neither  purposed  nor  fore- 
seen!" Locke,  in  seeking  in  the  length  of  human  infancy  an  ex- 
planation of  the  beginnings  of  the  permanent  family,  has  forgotten, 
Rousseau  intimates,  another  characteristic  of  the  human  species — 
the  long  period  of  gestation.  When  this  is  borne  in  mind — as 
Rousseau's  criticism  implies — it  becomes  evident  that  the  proposed 
explanation  presupposes  the  thing  to  be  explained.  The  helpless- 
ness of  the  human  infant  certainly  would  not  have  united  the  par- 
ents unless  they  had  already,  for  a  considerable  period,  been  united ; 
and  if  their  union  had  endured  for  so  long,  it  is  not  obviously  neces- 
sary to  invoke  additional  explanations  to  account  for  its  having 
endured  longer — especially  as  the  period  of  helplessness,  Rousseau 
suggests,  was  probably  much  briefer  in  the  case  of  primitive  man. 
At  all  events,  the  first  and  great  transition — that  from  casual  mat- 
ings  to  relatively  lasting  cohabitation  of  the  sexes — is  left  unex- 
plained by  the  theory  in  question.  Thus — for  these  and  other  rea- 
sons— Rousseau  concludes  that  le  raisonnement  de  Locke  tombe  en 
ruine. 

He  would  probably  have  pronounced  a  similar  judgment  on 
later  examples  of  the  same  argument.  For  the  weakness  of  the 
argument  should  have  been  still  clearer  by  the  time  it  was  revived 
in  the  late  19th  century.  It  was  then  well  known  to  naturalists 
that  the  family  is  not  peculiar  to  man;  and  that,  apparently,  "in 
the  higher  apes  monogamy  is  the  rule,  the  male  and  female  roam- 
ing at  large  in  a  family  party."*  The  gorilla,  for  example,  "lives 
in  a  society  consisting  of  male  and  female,  and  their  young  of  vari- 
ous ages  and  the  family  group  inhabits  the  recesses  of  the  forest. 
.  .  .  The  male  animal  spends  the  night  crouching  at  the  foot  of  the 
tree,  and  thus  protects  the  female  and  their  young,  which  are  in 
the  nest  above,  from  the  nocturnal  attacks  of  leopards."7  Fiske 
ignored  the  zoological  knowledge  of  his  time  in  declaring  that 
1 '  while  mammals  lower  than  man  are  gregarious, "  it  is  only  in  man 
that  there  "have  become  established  those  peculiar  relationships 
which  constitute  what  we  know  as  the  family."8  The  fact  is 
simply  that  some  species  are  of  a  monogamous  or  monandrous  habit, 
and  that  the  ancestors  of  man  were  probably  of  such  a  species. 

«  Pycroft,  The  Courtship  of  Animal*,  1914,  p.  26. 

T  Hartmann,  Anthropoid  Apes  (1885),  p.  231.  Garner,  howerer,  describes 
both  gorilla  and  chimpanzee  as  monandrous  but  not  usually  monogamous.  ' '  The 
chimpanzee,"  he  asserts,  "keeps  his  children  with  him  until  they  are  old 
enough  to  go  away  and  rear  families  of  their  own."  (Apes  and  Monkeys,  1900, 
pp.  99,  232.) 

>  The  Meaning  of  Infancy,  p.  29. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  385 

Why  an  animal  has  this  characteristic  we  do  not  know.  The  theory 
of  natural  selection  would,  indeed,  suggest  that  if  the  young  of  a 
species  remain  helpless  for  a  long  period,  that  species  is  more  likely 
to  survive  if  the  male  remains  with  the  female  and  aids  her  to  de- 
fend the  young.  But  this  would  only  mean  that  a  primarily  un- 
favorable variation — helpless  infancy — was  accompanied  by  an- 
other variation  which  in  some  degree  offset  its  disadvantages.  The 
latter  variation  can  not  have  been  caused  by  its  effect — the  better 
protection  of  the  young;  and  it  therefore  is  not  explained  by  that 
effect.  And  it  must,  as  Rousseau's  observation  suggests,  have  mani- 
fested itself  primarily  as  an  instinct  to  continue  with  the  same  mate 
or  (in  the  case  of  the  male,  in  some  species)  mates,  before  the  birth 
of  offspring.  Fiske  fell  into  an  extraordinary  inversion  of  causal 
relations,  and  at  the  same  time  missed  the  fact  that  really  needed 
to  be  accounted  for,  when  he  wrote  that  "one  effect  [of  lengthened 
infancy]  of  stupendous  importance"  was  that,  among  our  "half- 
human  forefathers,"  as  "helpless  babyhood  came  more  and  more 
to  depend  on  parental  care,  the  fleeting  sexual  relationships  estab- 
lished among  mammals  were  gradually  exchanged  for  permanent 
relations. ' ' 

As  an  explanation  of  the  origin  of  the  family,  then,  Fiske 's 
theory  was  neither  new  nor  true.  Nor  did  it  show  the  "value," 
in  the  sense  of  the  indispensability,  of  prolonged  infancy,  even  as 
a  means  to  man's  greater  intellectual  attainments.  It  was  not  evi- 
dent that  the  continued  plasticity  requisite  for  the  learning-process 
need  be  inseparable  from  physical  helplessness. 

ARTHUR  0.  LOVEJOY. 

JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Nietzsche,  sa  Vie  et  sa  Pensee.    Vol.  Ill ;  Le  Pessimisme  Esthetique 
de  Nietzsche,  sa  Philos&phie  a  I'Epoque  Wagnerienne.    CHARLES 
ANDLER.    Paris:  Editions  Bossard.    1921.    Pp.  390. 
Nietzsche's  mental   curiosity  knew  no  bounds.     So,   difference 
of  opinion  might  well  arise  over  the  crowding  recitals  of  Volume  II 
(c/.  this  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIX,  No.  11),  especially  with  reference  to 
the  relative  importance  of  the  influences  exerted  by  persons  and, 
no  less,  by  ideas  "in  the  air."    Nevertheless,  such  opportunities  for 
divergence,  seeing  that  they  are  capable  of  control  to  some  extent, 
pale  when  we  come  to  Volume  III  with  its  attempt  at  synthetic 
treatment  of  the  Nietzschean  "philosophy,"  and  its  search    (in- 
evitable it  would  seem),  for  "system"   (c/.  Bibliographical  Note, 


386  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

p.  20).  The  volume  contains  an  Introduction  (discussing  the  "phi- 
losophy") :  three  Books — "The  Origins  and  Renaissance  of 
Tragedy";  "The  Origins  and  Renaissance  of  Philosophy";  "The 
Origins  and  Renaissance  of  Civilization":  and  a  Conclusion  (con- 
cerned chiefly  with  Nietzsche's  pet  idea  of  a  "philosophy  of  civil- 
ization"). 

The  Introduction  assumes,  sans  phrases,  that  Nietzsche  was  a 
philosopher;  and  proceeds  to  an  interesting  exhibit  of  his  relation 
to  "system."  Andler  takes  care  to  emphasize  the  four  styles  of 
composition  and,  as  concerns  "system,"  points  out  that  "an  invis- 
ible force  tends  to  weld  the  numerous  fragments."  Therefore,  in 
his  reconstruction,  he  confesses  to  "preoccupation  with  the  history 
of  ideas,  not  of  literary  fragments"  (p.  27  note).  He  finds  that 
three  Periods  emerge  successively:  "Romantic  Pessimism"  (1869- 
76);  "Sceptical  Positivism"  (1876-81);  "Reconstruction"  (1882- 
8).  The  question  whether  Nietzsche  ever  thought  philosophically 
is  not  raised  and,  although  the  likeness  to  Plato  finds  recognition 
(cf.  Bk.  II.,  Ch.  II.,  Sect.  IV.),  perhaps  for  this  very  reason,  the 
approach  is  that  of  a  literary  man  rather  than  of  a  philosophical 
expert.  Nay,  the  hand  takes  color  from  the  dye  in  which  it  works. 
For,  the  emotion  of  superior  spirits  "n'est  que  I'elan  irresistible 
avec  lequel  leur  esprit  se  hate  vers  le  terme  ou  le  raisonnement  vul- 
gaire  s'achemine  avec  une  lenteur  reflechie"  (p.  16).  In  short,  we 
have  a  continuation  (raised  to  the  nth  power,  if  you  please,)  of 
prepotent  Romantic  Kulturgeschichte,  sublimely  stepping  from 
peak  to  peak  in  seven-leagued  boots.  And  yet,  the  apostle  of  "ex- 
treme relativism"  is  to  arrive  at  an  absolute. 

"M'insegnavate  come  I'uom'  s'eterna." 

We  must  have  patience  for  a  while,  hoping  to  find  some  resolution 
of  the  impasse  as  the  drama  unfolds  further. 

Chapter  I  of  Book  I  gives  a  straightforward  account  of  views 
about  the  origin  of  Greek  tragedy,  and  of  Nietzsche's  attitude  to 
the  problem.  There  is  an  informing  philological  note  on  his  pro- 
jected Hellenic  writings,  and  on  the  seven  plans  for  the  Birth  of 
Tragedy,  itself  a  fragment  of  the  larger  work  on  the  Greeks,  never 
written.  The  hesitation  due  to  clash  between  ideas  derived  from 
Schopenhauer  and  Wagner  receives  due  consideration.  Nietzsche's 
well-known  judgments  on  the  parts  played  respectively  by  JEschy- 
lus,  Sophocles,  and  Euripides-Socrates  are  summarized  neatly. 
Chapter  II  tells  why  Nietzsche  saw  the  resurrection  of  Greek 
tragedy  in  the  Wagnerian  drama,  explaining  the  parallel  factors 
of  the  "Dionysiac  soul,"  the  "faculty  for  mythology,"  and  the 
"artistic  audience."  Art  proves  once  more  that  men  are  better 


BOOK  REVIEWS  387 

than  "voracious  and  monstrous"  Nature.  Chapter  III  gives  a  com- 
petent summary  of  the  "quarrel  over  Greek  tragedy"  resultant 
upon  the  scrap — the  name  is  not  too  undignified — between  Nietz- 
sche, Wilamowitz,  Rohde,  and  Wagner.  Having  assessed  the  rights 
and  wrongs,  Andler  proceeds  to  show  how  this  youthful  emeute  de- 
termined the  positions  of  Wilamowitz  and  Rohde  throughout  life, 
and  concludes  with  an  outline  of  recent  tendencies  in  investigation, 
tracing  the  dead  hand  of  Nietzsche  in  many  ways. 

Book  II  treats  Philosophy  after  similar  fashion,  delineating 
Nietzsche's  attitude  ("the  philosopher  is  the  physician  of  Kultur"), 
and  his  peculiar  views  about  the  Pre-Socratics  and  Socrates,  in 
Chapter  I.  Chapter  II  brings  us  at  one  fell  swoop  to  modern  phi- 
losophy, with  its  "savants  submerged  in  the  infinitely  little,"  Scho- 
penhauer the  bright,  particular  exception.  But,  whatever  his  in- 
tellectual power,  the  crass  vulgarities  of  the  Frankfort  curmudgeon 
prevented  him  from  being  the  philosophical  Moses.  Hence,  as 
Andler  points  out,  following  Frau  Foster  (p.  155),  the  ideal  thinker 
was  drawn  by  Nietzsche  from  himself,  decked  with  certain  traits 
from  Wagner — not  Goethe.  And  so  we  are  led  to  the  "Platonism 
of  Nietzsche,"  interpreted  persuasively.  With  Chapter  III,  "The 
First  System  of  Nietzsche,  or  Philosophy  of  Illusion,"  we  find  our- 
selves, for  the  first  time  decisively,  in  full  tide  of  controversial  af- 
fairs. Differing  sharply  from  Raoul  Richter,  for  example,  who 
says  that  Nietzsche  was  "unsystematic,  confused,  and  dilettante" 
at  this  stage,  Andler  affirms  "the  total  cohesion  of  his  thought"  (p. 
172),  admitting  the  audacity  of  the  standpoint.  The  remainder  of 
the  volume  is,  in  effect,  proof.  Indeed,  so  much  so  that,  on  p.  302, 
when  the  conclusion  of  the  whole  matter  looms  in  sight,  Andler  can 
affirm,  Nietzsche's  "systematic  thought  is  of  marvellous  continu- 
ity." 

The  causes  of  the  "illusions"  of  knowledge,  morality  and  art 
exposed,  we  find  that,  between  1870  and  1874,  Nietzsche  fell  back 
upon  an  "impersonal  memory"  and  a  "collective  imagination," 
taking  metonymy  for  cool  reason ;  in  fact,  falling  victim  to  an  obvi- 
ous phase  of  the  substance-attribute  fallacy,  not  abandoned  till 
after  1876.  The  general  spirit  is  that  of  Schopenhauer,  tempered 
by  the  Wagnerian  dogma  of  musical  ecstasy  as  a  "veritable  phil- 
osophic revelation."  But  Lamarck  and  Emerson  work  like  yeast, 
with  the  result  that  Nietzsche  begins  to  "slip."  He  realizes  that 
"transformations"  are  imperative,  and  can  be  accomplished  by 
the  "internal  energy  which  upholds  all  life."  Accordingly,  a 
"practical"  metaphysic,  in  the  form  of  a  theory  of  civilization,  as- 
serts itself.  Book  III  is  devoted  to  a  "reconstruction"  of  this. 


388  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Chapter  I  deals  with  Greek  civilization,  which  seconds  Schopen- 
hauer's psychology,  but  contradicts  Nietzsche's  nascent  conception 
of  value  (p.  225).  Chapters  II  and  III  show  that,  in  face  of 
modern  philistinism,  Wagner  plays  the  role  of  a  " counter- Alexan- 
der," while  Germany  may  be  destined  to  enact  that  of  a  messiah. 
We  learn  that  the  idea  of  "value"  may  be  reconstituted  by  the 
"immense  reserve  energy  of  heroes,  thinkers,  artists."  But,  to 
this  end,  these  seminal  persons  must  rise  superior  to  the  three 
great  ogres — the  State,  Capitalism,  and  Science,  bemused  by  the 
fatal  belief  that  man  has  a  natural  right  to  happiness.  The  hod- 
men of  feudalized  science  know  as  little  of  real  life  as  their  more 
ignorant  contemporaries.  Debility  or  cynicism  leave  their  blight- 
ing trail  everywhere.  Even  the  fair  humanities  produce  mere 
"des  hommes  enregimentes"  (p.  390).  "Reconstruction"  of  the 
Prometheus  fragment  issues  in  suggestions  as  to  the  new  culture, 
and  presages  the  fateful  doctrine  of  "eternal  return." 

Thanks  to  a  misprint,  common  to  text  and  to  Table  des  Matieres, 
there  is  no  Chapter  IV.  Chapter  V  exhibits  Nietzsche's  plan  for 
the  reorganization  of  education,  necessary  to  rid  the  innocent  youth 
of  "false  culture,  the  journalistic  spirit,  and  superficial  rhetoric" 
(p.  305).  Chapter  VI  gives  a  subtle  exposition  of  the  part  which 
Nietzsche  expected  Bayreuth  to  play  in  this  transformation,  and  in- 
dicates how  a  "New  Wagnerism"  formulated  itself  in  his  mind, 
rendering  a  break  with  the  composer  inevitable"  (p.  318).  Nietz- 
sche's limitations  and  positive  errors  at  the  moment  are  set  forth 
(p.  326  f.).  Despite  them,  however,  Wagner's  "dynamism"  pre- 
figures Zarathustra.  The  outcome  of  the  first  period  is  the  convic- 
tion that  a  superior  civilization  must  be  developed ;  and  even  Scho- 
penhauer was  full  of  obscurity  on  this  point,  while  Wagner,  after 
arousing  great  expectations,  fell  from  grace.  So  Nietzsche  came  to 
sense  the  need  for  other  guides,  and  turned  to  the  French  moral- 
ists. 

The  Conclusion  furnishes  a  most  instructive  account  of  Nietz- 
sche's attitude  towards  the  problem  of  civilization;  of  his  debt  to 
Greek  culture,  and  to  the  Greek  intellect  which  followed  the  ques- 
tion whithersoever  it  led ;  and  of  his  personal  philosophy  at  this  time. 
Nietzsche  committed  himself  to  no  choice  between  "  intellectualism, 
naturalism,  and  personalism, "  finding  defects  in  all.  He  proceeded 
to  correct  them  by  a  new  apriorism  of  values,  simulating  the  system 
of  the  elder  Fichte — a  very  suggestive  remark,  not  elaborated! 
Recall  von  Hart  ma  mi's  unacknowledged  plunder  from  the  same 
source!  This  philosophy,  motivated  by  "liberty  of  the  spirit," 
brought  him  into  conflict  (or  competition)  with  the  personal  revela- 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

tion  of  Jesus.    "La  loi  de  genie  serait  heteronomie  pour  la  foule. 
La  loi  des  foules  est  heteronomie  pour  le  genie"  (p.  379). 

Two  questions,  and  one  request,  are  in  order.  What  are  we  to 
hear  of  the  influence  of  Ludwig  Feuerbach,  who  dominated  thought 
in  Germany  and  Teutonic  Switzerland  1845-65?  whose  Wesen 
des  Christ enthums  was  "the  third  crow  of  the  cock  of  the  spirit  of 
German  liberty"?  (c/.  Washington  University  Studies,  Vol.  IX, 
No.  1  (St.  Louis,  1921),  pp.  32  f.).  He  it  was  who  gave  Wagner 
his  start.  Of  his  less  important  oldest  brother,  Anselm,  the  archae- 
ologist, we  heard  a  good*  deal  in  volume  II  (pp.  229  f.).  Again, 
what  direct  contact,  if  any,  had  Nietzsche  with  Count  Arthur  de 
Gobineau?  This  seems  to  me  a  question  at  once  most  obscure  and 
most  seductive.  Finally,  I  beg  M.  Andler  to  furnish  a  complete 
index.  His  volume  must  be  thumbed  by  all  Nietzsche  scholars  and, 
for  this  purpose,  the  present  tables  des  matieres  are  quite  inade- 
quate. 

R.  M.  WENLET. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  MICHIGAN. 


Philosophy  and  the  New  Physics.  An  Essay  on  the  Relativity 
Theory  and,  the  Theory  of  Quanta.  Louis  ROUGIER.  Translated 
by  Morton  Masius.  Philadelphia:  P.  Blakiston's  Son  and  Com- 
pany. 1921.  Pp.  xv  +  159. 

The  title  of  this  essay  in  the  original  French — La  Materialization 
de  I'finergie — is  more  exactly  descriptive  of  it  than  the  English 
substitute.  There  is  in  fact  almost  nothing  in  the  book  in  the  way 
of  metaphysical  generalization  from  the  physical  theories  that  are 
examined;  and  there  is  but  a  page  or  two  of  comment  on  the  im- 
portance for  physical  theory  of  the  pragmatist  conception  of  truth. 
The  book  should  be  none  the  less  interesting  to  philosophical  readers. 
Those  who  have  given  some  serious  attention  to  recent  advances 
in  physics  will  be  glad  to  find  this  well-ordered  and  illuminating 
summary.  Those  who  would  like  to  set  about  the  study  will  find 
the  field  mapped  out  for  them,  and  a  useful  bibliography  of  French, 
as  well  as  German,  books  and  articles.  And  those  whose  interests 
lie  elsewhere  will  find  here  the  means  of  ' '  speaking  with  an  appear- 
ance of  wisdom"  upon  these  important  topics. 

THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA. 
BRYN  MAWR  COLLEGE. 


390  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

JOURNAL  OP  EDUCATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY,  October, 
1921.  The  Reading  Problem  in  Arithmetic:  PAUL  W.  TERRY  (pp. 
365-377). -It  has  become  recognized  that  a  definite  and  distinctive 
problem  in  reading  is  to  be  found  in  each  of  the  elementary-school 
subjects.  An  investigation  was  conducted  on  the  reading  problem 
in  arithmetic.  The  records  show  that  the  numerals  of  problems  make 
decidedly  greater  demands  upon  attention  than  the  accompanying 
words.  Less  than  half  as  many  digits  as  letters  are  perceived  dur- 
ing one  pause  of  the  eye.  An  Experimental  and  Statistical  Study 
of  Reading  and  Reading  Tests:  A.  I.  GATES  (pp.  378-392). -The 
second  instalment ;  concluded  in  the  November  issue.  The  Results  of 
Retests  by  Means  of  the  Binet  Scale:  J.  E.  W.  WALUN  (pp.  392- 
401). -The  study  is  based  on  two  testings  of  136  cases,  three  testings 
of  16  of  these  cases  and  a  fourth  testing  of  one.  The  intervals 
varied,  the  average  between  the  first  and  second  tests  was  2.2  years, 
range  %  to  6  years.  The  average  interval  between  the  second  and 
third  tests  was  two  years,  range  1  to  4  years.  The  necessity  of  vali- 
dating the  accuracy  of  the  Stanford  norms — and  revising  the  tests 
and  administrative  procedure — on  the  basis  of  the  testing  of  a  large 
number  of  unselected  children  from  various  sections  of  the  country 
is  urgent.  The  tentative  conclusion  is  that  most  of  the  Stanford  age 
norms  are  too  difficult,  thus  exaggerating  the  subjects'  deficiency. 
Mental  Growth  and  the  I.  Q.:  L.  M.  TERMAN  (pp.  401-407 ) .-Sev- 
eral other  contributions  on  the  validity  of  the  I.  Q.  are  mentioned. 
Criteria  to  Employ  in  Choice  of  Tests:  R.  FRANZEN  and  F.  B.  KNIGHT 
(pp.  408-412). -We  should  insist  upon  the  use  of  tests  which  can  be 
proven  to  test  what  they  purport  to  measure,  which  are  reliable  and 
objective,  which  are  scaled  and  which  have  well-defined 
norms  based  on  sufficient  material.  Personal  Judgments:  E.  E. 
LINDSAY  (pp.  413-415). -Teachers'  estimates  of  children's  native 
capacities  and  these  capacities  as  determined  by  as  scientific  method 
as  possible,  were  compared.  Seven  members  of  a  teaching  group 
judged  students  after  a  month's  class-room  acquaintance.  The  group 
judging  was  a  highly  selected  one  and  the  group  judged  was  small. 
The  conclusions  drawn  are  (1)  Teachers'  estimates  of  children's  na- 
tive capacity  are  significant  but  to  no  marked  degree,  (2)  training 
and  experience  of  the  teacher  do  not  seem  greatly  to  affect  this 
significance,  (3)  individual  judgment  of  the  same  children  by  obser- 
vers with  approximately  the  same  contact  differ  widely,  (4)  other 
factors  than  native  ability  to  enter  into  one's  judgment  of  same. 
Notes.  New  Publications. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  391 

SCIENTIA.  December,  1921.  La  loi  des  grands  nombres  (pp. 
433-438):  C.  V.  L.  CHABLIER  (Lund). -La  Place's  world-formula, 
even  if  it  found  the  intellect  who  could  deductively  think  it  through, 
could  never  be  established  on  the  basis  of  observation,  for  observa- 
tion is  essentially  approximate.  All  science  is,  therefore,  of  neces- 
sity statistical,  and  deals  with  average  effects,  not  with  individuals. 
Geological  Conquest  of  the  Air  (pp.  439-446)  :  CHARLES  R.  KEYES 
(Des  Moines)  .-Only  recently  have  we  come  to  realize  the  power  of 
the  wind  to  shape  topography,  particularly  in  the  arid  desert  lands. 
Le  type  chimique  et  la  substance  des  corps  simples  (pp.  447-454)  : 
MAURICE  DE  BROGLIE  (Paris)  .-Summary  of  facts  about  isotopes, 
with  emphasis  on  their  fundamental  character  for  the  most  recent 
chemistry.  Les  dommages  economiques  mondiaux  causes  par  la 
guerre  (pp.  455-466):  FILXPPO  VIRGILII  (Siena.)  .-Shows  the  com- 
plexity of  the  calculations  of  war  costs,  and  the  elements  of  gain 
that  must  also  be  taken  into  account,  yet  concludes  tha,t  2500  billion 
francs  of  loss  remain,  a  terrible  drain  on  all  humanity.  La  ques- 
tion sociale:  elargissons  le  socialisme  (pp.  467-472)  :  GEORGES 
RENARD  (Paris) .-Decidedly  idealistic  sketch  of  a  programme  of 
reform.  La  theorie  de  I' evolution  en  neuropathologie  (pp.  473- 
479)  :  MARIO  CARRARA  (Turin). -The  more  recently  evolved  the  re- 
action, the  more  easily  is  it  subject  to  pathological  alterations. 
Reviews  of  Scientific  Books  and  Periodicals. 

Lavelle,  Louis.  La  Dialectique  du  Monde  sensible.  Oxford  and 
New  York :  Oxford  University  Press.  1921.  Pp.  xli  -f  232. 

Lavelle,  Louis.  La  Perception  de  la  Pronfondeur.  Oxford  and  New 
York :  Oxford  University  Press.  1921.  Pp.  72. 

de  Tourtoulon,  Pierre.  Philosophy  in  the  Development  of  Law. 
Translated  by  Martha  McC.  Read.  New  York:  The  Macmillan 
Co.  1922.  Pp.  lii  +  635.  $5. 

Heermance,  Edgar  L.  Chaos  or  Cosmos.  New  York :  E.  P.  Dutton 
&  Co.  1922.  Pp.  xxi  -f  358.  $3. 

Malebranche.  Entretiens  sur  la  Metaphysique  et  sur  la  Religion 
suivis  d'extraits  des  Entretiens  sur  la  Mort.  (Publies  par  Paul 
Fontana).  2  volumes.  (Collection  Les  Classiques  de  la  Phi- 
losophic) .  Paris :  Librairie  Armand  Colin.  1922.  Pp.  xii  -+- 192, 
190.  6  fr.  50  each. 

Santayana,  George.  Soliloquies  in  England  and  later  Soliloquies. 
New  York:  Charles  Scribner's  Sons.  1922.  Pp.  264. 


392  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

NOTES  AND  NEWS 

The  following  article  is  taken  from  Science,  May  12,  1922: 
The  teaching  of  evolution  in  the  Baptist  denominational 
schools  in  Texas  is  being  investigated  as  heretical.  The  denomina- 
tion is  strong  in  membership  and  maintains  about  fifteen  colleges 
and  seminaries  in  the  state,  the  chief  of  which  is  Baylor  University 
at  Waco.  It  appears  that  the  trouble  arose  as  the  result  of  the 
publication  in  1920,  by  the  Baylor  University  Press  itself,  of  an 
"Introduction  to  the  Principles  of  Sociology,"  by  Grove  Samuel 
Dow,  Professor  of  Sociology  in  Baylor  University.  The  book  is 
based  upon  the  theory  of  evolution  wherever  it  touches  upon  the 
biological  aspects  of  sociology,  although  the  term  biological  evolu- 
tion is  scarcely  or  not  at  all  used  in  the  text.  At  a  recent  confer- 
ence of  representatives  of  the  Baptists  of  all  parts  of  the  state,  such 
teachings  were  pronounced  heresy,  and  a  sweeping  investigation  is 
being  made  of  all  of  the  Baptist  schools  of  the  state  to  determine 
how  much  "heresy"  is  being  taught.  Professor  Dow  has  resigned 
his  position. 

A  somewhat  related  situation  has  existed  at  Southern  Method- 
ist University,  Dallas,  where  the  teaching  of  Dr.  John  A.  Rice, 
Professor  of  Old  Testament  Interpretation,  has  created  the  severe 
opposition  of  a  large  part  of  his  church.  Dr.  Rice's  book,  "The 
Old  Testament  in  the  Life  of  Today,"  looks  upon  the  Old  Testa- 
ment as  a  series  of  independent  historical  papers,  each  subject  to 
its  own  interpretation.  Many  are  considered  as  having  been  re- 
vised by  several  authors  before  they  have  reached  their  present 
form.  Each  is  regarded  as  a  literary  production,  subject  to  all  of 
the  rules  of  literary  interpretation ;  this  introduces  a  personal  fac- 
tor into  any  understanding  of  the  Old  Testament,  and  completely 
does  away  with  literal  interpretations.  Dr.  Rice  has  also  left  his 
position,  to  become  pastor  of  a  Methodist  church  in  another  state. 

S.  A.  R. 

At  Columbia  University,  the  following  promotions  in  psychology 
have  been  announced:  Dr.  H.  L.  Hollingworth  to  a  full  professor- 
ship at  Barnard  College;  Dr.  Arthus  I.  Gates,  Dr.  William  A.  Mc- 
Call  and  Dr.  Leta  S.  Hollingworth  to  associate  professorships  at 
Teachers  College;  Dr.  A.  T.  Poffenberger  to  an  associate  professor- 
ship at  Columbia  Unirersity. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  15  JULY  20,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE— I 

INTRODUCTION 

The  topic  of  the  present  study  is  to  be  understood  in  a  very  re- 
stricted sense,  and  the  essential  restrictions  must  be  made  plain  at 
the  outset.  Every  textbook  of  geometry  may  be  said  to  be  an  essay 
on  the  nature  of  space,  that  is  to  say,  of  space  in  the  abstract — space 
assumed  either  as  matter  of  fact  or  as  matter  of  hypothesis.  This 
little  essay  does  not  pretend  to  rival  the  textbooks  of  geometry.  It 
does,  indeed,  have  occasion  to  treat  of  some  very  elementary  ge- 
ometrical concepts,  but  not  of  anything  more  complicated  than  the 
straight  line.  At  the  same  time,  it  is  not  content  to  assume  ab- 
stract space,  either  as  matter  of  fact  or  as  hypothesis.  On  the  con- 
trary, its  princiapl  object  is  to  exhibit  the  conception  of  space  in 
its  actual  setting  in  experience. 

However,  it  is  not  the  intention  to  try  to  give  an  account  of  the 
whole  of  this  setting,  but  only  of  so  much  of  it  as  is  strictly  relevant 
to  the  geometrical  treatment  of  space.  With  the  further  physical 
aspects  of  space  we  shall  have  almost  nothing  to  do.  The  notion  of 
mass  and  the  notion,  of  a  measurable  duration  will  not  enter  into 
our  discussion — not  to  speak  of  the  notions  of  force  and  energy. 
But  a  very  important  aspect  of  the  meaning  of  distance  consists  in 
its  relations  to  mass,  duration,  etc.  No  man  can  throw  a  baseball 
two  hundred  yards;  and  no  man  can  run  a  mile  in  three  minutes. 
From  the  geometrical  point  of  view,  the  kilometer  has  no  properties 
distinct  from  those  of  the  millimeter ;  and  if  all  the  distances  in  the 
world  were  multiplied  by  a  million  there  would  be  no  change  at  all. 
From  the  physical  point  of  view,  even  the  doubling  of  all  lengths 
and  distances  would  have  a  very  profound  effect  upon  the  world,  if 
bodies  on  the  surface  of  the  earth  continued  to  fall  about  sixteen 
feet  during  the  first  second. 

The  reader  will,  therefore,  realize  that  in  restricting  considera- 
tion to  the  geometrical  conception  of  space,  we  very  greatly  simplify 
our  problem,  and  at  the  same  time  seriously  limit  the  possible  value 
of  any  solution  which  we  may  reach.  However  successful  we  may 
be,  we  shall  have  taken  but  a  single  step  toward  the  larger  syste- 
matic knowledge  of  space,  which  can  only  be  obtained  as  an  essential 
part  of  the  knowledge  of  the  general  character  of  the  physical  world. 

393 


394  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Tin-re  are  two  motives  for  this  restriction  of  the  inquiry.  One 
is  purely  personal:  the  narrowness  of  the  writer's  knowledge  and 
competence.  This,  if  it  stood  alone,  would  be  a  better  reason  for 
not  publishing  at  all  than  for  publishing  the  result  of  a  truncated 
investigation.  But  there  is  a  further  motive  in  the  belief  that 
within  the  limits  that  are  thus  laid  down  a  tolerably  complete  and 
satisfactory  solution  of  the  problem  can  be  given. 

There  is  this  also  to  be  said.  While  results,  such  as  are  here 
given,  are  seriously  limited  in  their  range,  they  have  a  place  of  their 
own  in  the  system  of  science ;  and  at  the  present  juncture  their  im- 
portance may  be  very  great.  How  far  Professor  Einstein  has  gone 
into  detail  in  this  matter,  I  do  not  know;  but  it  is  clear  from  his 
account  of  the  use  of  "measuring-rods"  that  some  such  theory  as 
that  here  set  forth  is  presupposed  by  him  in  his  two-fold  theory  of 
relativity.  Professor  Whitehead,  who  is  the  author  both  of  an  in- 
dependent account  of  the  electromagnetic  theory  of  relativity  and 
of  a  revision  of  Newton's  theory  of  gravitation,  has  set  forth  very 
fully  his  conception  of  spatial  order  and  measurement  in  two  re- 
markable volumes,  An  Enquiry  into  the  Principles  of  Natural 
Knowledge  and  The  Concept  of  Nature.  That  conception  is  radi- 
cally inconsistent  with  the  analysis  here  given. 

Certain  of  the  differences  between  Professor  Whitehead 's  ac- 
count and  the  present  one  may  be  specified  as  follows.  His  account 
starts  with  events;  the  present  account  starts  with  a  certain  class 
of  objects,  namely,  physical  solids.  Among  the  events  which  he  as- 
sumes, some  are  unlimited  in  three  dimensions;  here  only  finite 
solids  are  assumed.  The  assumed  unlimited  events  have,  with 
reference  to  their  fourth  (temporal)  dimension,  a  definite  shape; 
they  are  analogous  to  the  three-dimensional  space  between  parallel 
planes;  the  solids  from  which  the  present  account  starts  are  of  all 
possible  shapes,  but  no  one  shape  is  assumed  as  given.  Most  im- 
portant of  all,  however,  is  the  fact  that  Professor  Whitehead  makes 
the  conceptions  of  the  point,  line,  and  surface — and  the  solid,  too, 
for  that  matter — as  well  as  of  linear  order,  length,  and  distance, 
logically  dependent  upon  the  intersection  of  moments  of  different 
time-systems;  while  to  me  this  appears  to  be  a  most  unfortunate 
distortion  of  the  actual  system  of  relationships. 

There  is  a  deeper  ground  of  difference,  however,  which  ought 
not  to  pass  unnoticed.  Professor  Whitehead 's  work  is  based  upon 
a  certain  theory  as  to  the  nature  of  experience,  which  seems  to  me 
to  be  extremely  doubtful.  He  takes  his  start  from  certain  data, 
which,  as  he  believes,  are  given  to  us  in  sensuous  experience.  My 
own  point  of  departure  is  in  the  behavior  of  things  toward  one  an- 
other, as  we  manipulate  them. 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  395 

Among  Professor  Whitehead's  incontestably  important  contri- 
butions is  his  method  of  "extensive  abstraction."  In  the  precise 
form  in  which  he  has  described  it,  it  was  not  available  for  my  pur- 
poses. But,  in  an  appendix,  I  have  used  a  simplified,  and  in  some 
respects  strengthened,  form  of  the  method  for  the  definition  of  the 
point,  the  line,  and  the  surface  as  sets  of  solids;  and  I  have  at  the 
same  time  showed  how  the  method  is  related  to  my  own  assump- 
tions. 

The  main  body  of  the  essay  is  in  two  parts.  The  first  is  mathe- 
matical; but,  lest  this  should  affright  any  modest  philosophical 
reader,  let  me  hasten  to  add  that  the  mathematics  is  of  the  very 
simplest  character — quite  as  easy  as  the  easiest  pages  of  the  first 
book  of  Euclid.  (In  the  notes  there  are  passages  that  may  make 
rather  more  difficult  reading;  but  these  are  not  essential.)  The  ob- 
ject of  this  part  is  to  lead  to  as  clear  as  possible  a  conception  of 
certain  of  the  more  fundamental  geometrical  entities  and  relations. 

The  second  part  is  physical.  Its  object  is  to  determine  the  em- 
pirical foundations  of  geometry  (so  far  as  these  may  properly  be 
held  to  lie  within  the  limits  of  a  physical,  rather  than  a  psychological, 
inquiry).  The  point  and  the  peculiar  relation  between  points, 
which,  in  the  mathematical  part,  figure  as  primary  assumptions  in 
terms  of  which  explanation  is  to  be  made,  are  here  themselves  the 
goal  that  is  to  be  attained.  The  physical  part  of  the  inquiry  is  thus 
directly  supplementary  to  the  mathematical.  The  former  owes  its 
problem  to  the  outcome  of  the  latter. 

At  the  end  of  the  second  part,  an  opportunity  arises  for  mak- 
ing a  suggestion  the  import  of  which  extends  far  beyond  the  sub- 
ject of  these  pages.  This  opportunity  is  afforded,  first,  by  the  close 
similarity  of  the  conception  here  reached  of  the  principles  of  ge- 
ometry, to  the  conception  of  physical  principles  long  ago  advanced 
by  Galileo,  as  well  as  to  that  recently  advanced  by  Poincare;  and, 
secondly,  by  a  further  analogy  to  the  general  principle  of  empiri- 
cal science — the  uniformity  of  nature.  I  shall  take  advantage  of 
this  opportunity  to  the  extent  of  offering  the  briefest  possible  com- 
ment.1 

1  With  the  exception  of  the  appendix  dealing  with  the  method  of  extensive 
abstraction,  this  essay  has  lain  in  manuscript  for  the  last  five  years.  An 
earlier,  more  general  study,  The  Nature  of  Primary  Qualities,  was  published 
in  the  Philosophical  Review  for  September,  1913  (Vol.  XXII,  pp.  502ff.).  A 
second  paper,  On  the  Distinction  between  Primary  and  Secondary  Qualities, 
dealing  more  fully  with  certain  outlying  epistemological  questions,  appeared 
in  this  JOURNAL  for  February  28,  1918  (Vol.  XV,  pp.  113ff.). 


396  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

THE  FUNDAMENTAL  CONCEPTS  OP  GEOMETRY 

Every  reader,  the  memory  of  whose  youthful  days  has  not  faded 
out  completely,  will  recall  that  in  the  study  of  elementary  geometry 
one  sets  out  from  a  body  of  concepts  that  are  accepted  as  too 
simple  and  clear  to  need  definition,  and  that  in  terms  of  these  pri- 
mary concepts  one  defines  all  other  concepts  that  belong  to  the  sci- 
ence. The  number  of  these  assumed  "indefinables"  is  usually  very 
great ;  but,  since  they  are  not  plainly  listed  and  set  apart,  they  may 
easily  seem  to  be  far  fewer  than  a  careful  search  would  show. 

It  has  long  been  an  enterprise  of  mathematicians,  dating  par- 
ticularly from  the  researches  of  Leibniz,  first,  to  make  an  accurate 
list  of  the  assumed  concepts  of  geometry,  and,  secondly,  to  reduce 
their  number  to  the  absolute  minimum  by  defining  all  that  can  be 
defined.  This  enterprise  has  in  recent  years  been  rewarded  with  a 
large  measure  of  success.  It  has  been  found  possible  to  base  the 
concepts  of  geometry  upon  two  "indefinables,"  one  of  which  is  an 
entity,  the  other  a  relation.2 

What  was  not  anticipated  in  the  old  days  is  the  fact  that  a  con- 
siderable freedom  of  choice  is  possible  in  choosing  the  indefinables. 
The  entity  chosen  is,  indeed,  usually  the  point.  But  for  the  rela- 
tion there  are  three  important  alternatives  to  choose  from,  giving 
rise  to  three  fairly  distinct  types  of  geometrical  system:  protective 
geometry,  descriptive  geometry,8  and  metrical  geometry. 

(i)  For  protective  geometry  the  indefinables  are  now  usually 
"point"  and  a  certain  relation  between  three  points  called  "to  be 

2  This  last  statement  must  not  be  misunderstood.     Geometry  makes   the 
freest  use  of  the  concepts  of  formal  logic,  as  well  as  of  the  more  complex 
mathematical  concepts    (particularly  those  of  arithmetic)    which  are  definable 
in   terms   of    logical   concepts.      Such    terms    as   "if — then,"    "and,"    "or," 
"not,"  "any,"  "such  as,"  "identical  with,"  etc.;  as  well  as  "one,"  "two," 
"as  many,"  "more,"  "twice  as  many,"  etc.,  are  thickly  sprinkled  all  over 
the  pages  of  our  geometries.     Some  of  these  must,  in  any  system  of  logic, 
be  accepted  as   indefinable.     When,  therefore,  we  speak  of  the   two  indefin- 
able* of  a  system  of  geometry,  we  mean  the  two  peculiar  indefinables,  assumed 
in  addition  to  the  omnipresent  concepts  of  logic. 

To  guard  against  misplaced  verbal  criticism,  it  may  be  added  that  there 
is  an  interpretation  of  geometry,  according  to  which  its  ' '  indefinables ' '  are 
really  defined — namely,  by  the  "axioms,"  or  "postulates,"  from  which  tie 
demonstrations  of  the  science  proceed.  The  argument  of  the  present  chapter 
is  unaffected  by  these  considerations. 

3  The  usage  of  this  term  is  unfortunately  inconsistent.     In  the  following 
pages  it  will  be  used  to  denote  the  type  of  geometry  for  which  measurement 
is  a  wholly  secondary  matter,  but  which  assumes  from  the  outset — as  projec- 
tive  geometry  does   not — the   conception   of  the   order  of   three   points   in   a 
straight  line.    Cf.  B.  Russell,  The  Principle*  of  Mathematics,  p.  382  and  Chap. 
XLVI;  L.  Couturat,  Let  Principet  de»  Mathematiqua,  p.  142  and  pp.  159ff. 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  397 

collinear."  In  common  language  this  relation  would  be  expressed 
by  saying  that  the  three  points  were  in  one  straight  line.  The  same 
mode  of  expression  may,  indeed,  be  used  by  the  mathematician ;  but 
he  has  then  three  indefinables  instead  of  two:  namely,  "point," 
"line"  (or  "straight  line"),  and  "to  be  in."  It  is  simpler  to  start 
with  "point"  and  "collinear,"  and  to  define  the  straight  line  as  a 
peculiar  set  of  points;  that  is  to  say,  as  the  set  of  all  the  points 
that  are  collinear  with  two  distinct  points,  together  with  the  two 
points  themselves. 

We  may  pause  here  to  emphasize  the  fact  that  collinearity  is  a 
relation  between  three  points.  The  relations  with  which  logic  has 
for  the  most  part  dealt  are  relations  between  two  terms ;  and  from 
this  fact  a  wide-spread  prejudice  has  arisen,  to  the  effect  that  all 
relations  are  confined  to  two  terms.  But  the  case  of  collinearity 
itself  is  clear  evidence  to  the  contrary.  Any  two  points  are  con- 
nected by  a  straight  line;  but  when  this  is  true  of  three  points  it 
constitutes  a  certain  definite  relation  between  them. 

It  is  true,  that  instead  of  regarding  collinearity  as  a  relation  be- 
tween three  points,  we  may  equally  well  regard  it  as  a  quality  of  a 
collection  of  three  points.4  That  is,  of  course,  because  the  relation 
of  collinearity  is  symmetrical.  If  A  is  collinear  with  B  and  C,  it  is 
collinear  with  C  and  B;  and  furthermore  B  is  collinear  with  A  and 
C,  and  C  is  collinear  with  A  and  B.  Such  a  relation  can  always 
be  regarded  as  a  quality  that  is  predicable  of  the  collection  as  a 
totality.  Instead  of  saying  that  Henry  is  a  cousin  of  Stephen  or 
that  Stephen  is  a  cousin  of  Henry,  I  may  equally  well  say  that 
Henry  and  Stephen  are  a  pair  of  cousins. 

(ii)  For  descriptive  geometry  the  approved  indefinables  are 
"point"  and  "to  be  between."  This  latter  is,  again,  a  relation  be- 
tween three  points.  It  would  be  expressed  in  ordinary  language  by 
saying  that  one  point  was  in  a  line  with  two  others,  and  between 
them;  but  in  descriptive  geometry  it  is  accepted  as  a  simple,  inex- 
plicable datum. 

The  between-relation  differs  from  the  relation  of  collinearity  in 
being  symmetrical  only  with  respect  to  two  of  the  three  points  and 
asymmetrical  with  respect  to  either  of  those  two  points  and  the 

*  The  properties  that  we  ascribe  to  things  are  of  two  sorts :  first,  those 
that  we  may  ascribe  to  a  single  thing  and,  secondly,  those  that  may  only  be 
ascribed  to  two  or  more  things  conjointly.  "To  be  brave"  is  an  example 
of  the  first  sort;  "to  be  a  cousin  of"  is  an  example  of  the  second  sort.  These 
two  sorts  of  properties  may,  with  essential  fidelity  to  tradition,  be  distinguished 
as  "qualities"  and  "relations."  It  should  be  observed,  however,  that  in 
accordance  with  this  usage,  while  "to  be  a  cousin  of"  is  a  relation,  "to  be  a 
cousin  of  Peter"  is  a  quality;  for  we  may  affirm  it  of  a  single  subject. 


398  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

third  point.  If  A  is  between  B  and  C,  then  it  is  between  C  and  B; 
but  B  is  not  between  A  and  C,  nor  is  C  between  A  and  B.5  Ac- 
cordingly the  between-relation  is  not  interpretable  as  a  quality  of 
the  collection  of  three  points.  The  peculiar  position  of  the  middle 
point  can  not  be  expressed  in  any  such  way.  The  relation  may, 
however,  be  regarded,  not  as  a  relation  between  three  terms,  but  as 
a  relation  between  two ;  namely,  the  middle  point  and  the  collection 
consisting  of  the  other  two  points. 

(iii)  Metrical  geometry  has  been  less  successful  than  the  other 
two  types  of  geometry  in  finding  appropriate  and  serviceable  in- 
definables.  Metrical  geometry  is  what  most  of  us  mean  when  we 
use  the  word  without  an  adjective — the  science  as  set  forth  by 
Euclid  and  his  direct  successors.  In  fact  the  expression  "metrical 
geometry"  is  etymologically  a  crude  tautology.  But  the  science  of 
space  has  been  so  extended  during  the  last  century,  that  its  original 
subject  of  spatial  measurement  has  become  for  it  an  altogether 
secondary  interest.  The  historical  fact  remains,  that  metrical  ge- 
ometry is  the  original  type,  and  that  projective  and  descriptive  ge- 
ometry are  comparatively  recent  specialized  developments  of  con- 
ceptions first  reached  by  the  metrical  mode  of  approach.  The  less 
satisfactory  condition  of  the  foundations  of  metrical  geometry 
must,  therefore,  be  deeply  regretted  by  those  who  wish  to  under- 
stand the  place  of  geometry  in  human  experience. 

Since  the  time  of  Leibniz,  the  generally  preferred  indefinables 
for  metrical  geometry  have  been  "point"  and  a  class  of  relations 
between  two  points,  called  ' '  distances. "  It  is  assumed  that  the  same 
relation  of  distance  that  subsists  between  two  points  may  also  sub- 
sist between  two  other  points.  As  a  matter  of  fact  the  distance  be- 
tween two  points  never  appears  in  a  proposition  except  as  it  is  in 
some  way  compared  with  the  distances  between  other  points. 

The  unsatisfactoriness  of  .these  indefinables  depends  upon  the 
awkwardness  of  the  procedure  by  which  it  is  necessary  to  introduce 
the  notion  of  one  distance  being  greater  than  another  distance.  The 
following  device  is  as  simple  as  any : 

.  ^  "The  distance  AB  is  greater  than  the  distance 

'  *  CD"  means  that  there  exists  a  point  T,  such 

that  the  distance  CT  is  the  same  as  the  dis- 

i  *'         T      tance  DT,  and  such  that  there  is  no  point  X 


such  that  the  distances  AX,  BX,  and  CT  are  all  the  same." 

s  Sometimes  a  certain  class  of  exceptions  is  admitted:  it  is  assumed  that 
any  point  ia  "between"  itself  and  any  other.  (In  the  same  way  it  may  be 
attorned  in  projective  geometry  that  any  point  ia  collinear  with  itself  and 
any  other  point.)  This  is  to  be  regarded  as  a  merely  verbal  matter,  to  be 
determined  by  convenience  of  terminology. 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  399 

It  is  to  be  observed  that  this  device  does  not  enable  us  to  define 
the  relation  "greater  than"  except  on  the  implied  assumption  that 
space  is  of  at  least  two  dimensions.  If  we  limit  space  to  a  single 
straight  line,  then,  if  the  distances  AB  and  CD  are  not  identical, 
AB  is  necessarily  greater  than  CD  by  the  above  definition;  for,  on 
that  supposition,  if  the  distances  CY  and  DY  were  the  same,  we 
could  never  find  a  point  X  such  that  AX,  BX,  and  CY  were  identi- 
cal. 

If  we  assume  that  space  is  of  only  one  dimension,  we  can,  in- 
deed, define  the  relation  "greater  than"  with  reference  to  any  two 
distances  that  are  commensurable  with  each  other.  We  say,  for 
example,  that  if  the  distances  AB,  BC,  CD,  and  DE  are  all  the  same, 
then  the  distance  AE  contains  the  distance  AB  four  times.  If, 
in  the  same  way,  the  distance  XY  contains  AB  three  times,  then, 
since  (in  the  arithmetical  sense  of  the  terms)  four  is  greater  than 
three,  we  say:  "AE  is  greater  than  XY."7 

How  unfortunate  it  is  that  the  relation  "greater  than"  should 
be  made  to  depend  upon  multidimensionality  or  else  upon  eom- 
mensurability,  is  seen  from  the  consideration  of  time.  Time  we  are 
in  the  habit  of  conceiving  on  the  analogy  of  the  straight  line,  as  a 
space  of  one  dimension.  Now,  in  the  case  of  time,  we  make  no 
scruple  to  assume  that  one  interval  may  be  longer  than  another, 
altogether  independently  of  the  question  of  commensurability. 
Why  should  we  have  to  look  outside  of  the  straight  line  itself  in 
order  to  give  a  general  meaning  to  the  proposition  that  one  of  its 
segments  is  greater  than  another?8 

When  we  reflect  upon  the  matter,  we  can  see  that  there  is  at 

«  This  figure  illustrates  the  fact  that  if  AB 
were  less  than  CD  a  point  X  that  satisfied  the 
given  requirement  could  easily  be  found.  It 
must,  however,  always  lie  outside  of  the  line  AB. 


7  It  might  be  supposed  that  this  mode  of  definition  could  be  extended 
to  incommensurable  distances  by  the  method  of  limits;  but  this  appears  to 
be  impossible.  One  can  not  even  give  a  meaning  to  the  expression,  "B  lies 
between  A  and  C,"  unless  AB  and  BC  are  commensurable. 

s  It  is,  of  course,  possible  to  assume  "  greater  -than "  (in  the  sense  of  a 
relation  between  two  distances)  as  a  third  geometrical  indefinable,  and  this 
is  sometimes,  openly  or  covertly,  done.  But  such  a  procedure,  if  it  is  not  un- 
avoidable, has  this  demerit:  it  puts  a  limitation  upon  the  understanding  of 
the  subject-matter  of  the  science — it  effectually  prevents  a  maximum  clearness. 
It  is  true  that  a  high  degree  of  simplicity  is  thereby  facilitated;  but  in  the 
study  of  the  principles  of  mathematics  simplicity  is  too  dearly  purchased  at 
the  expense  of  clearness.  Each  additional  undefined  term  that  might  have 


400  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

bottom  a  very  good  reason  why  the  distance-relation  makes  a  very 
poor  conception  upon  which  to  base  the  science  of  spatial  measure- 
ment. As  we  have  already  remarked,  one  distance-relation  never 
appears  alone  in  a  proposition,  but  only  in  comparison  with  another 
distance-relation.  Geometry  takes  cognizance  of  no  peculiar  prop- 
erties of  any  particular  distance.  Hence  the  distance  between  two 
given  points,  when  it  is  considered  by  itself,  apart  from  any  rela- 
tion to  the  distances  between  other  points,  is  as  nearly  as  possible 
an  empty  concept. 

This  may,  perhaps,  be  made  clearer  by  an  illustration.  Sup- 
pose a  man  cast  ashore  upon  a  desert  island,  where  among  the  use- 
ful articles  that  he  has  saved  from  the  wreck  he  finds  a  pair  of 
compasses  and  a  straight-edge,  but  no  yard-measure  and  nothing 
of  any  known  ratio  to  the  yard.  Can  he  reproduce  the  yard?  He 
can  not.  The  yard,  like  every  other  measure  of  length,  is  a  con- 
ventional unit.  To  be  a  yard  long  means  to  be  just  as  long  as  some- 
thing else  accepted  as  being  a  yard  long.  If  a  standard  of  reference 
is  wanting,  the  yard  disappears. 

The  suggestion  thus  arises  that  for  the  construction  of  a  metri- 
cal geometry  the  fundamental  relation  ought  to  be  a  relation  be- 
tween four  points,  or,  if  you  please,  between  two  "pairs"  of  points 
— collections  of  points  consisting  of  two  each.'  One  such  relation 
is  "to  be  just  as  far  apart  as."  Another  is  "to  be  farther  apart 

been  dispensed  with  means  so  much  more  superficiality — it  means  that  the 
labor  of  analysis  that  ought  to  be  done  haa  not  been  done. 

In  this  connection  the  remark  may  be  made,  that  the  number  of  assumed 
axioms — provided  these  are  mutually  independent  and  are  sufficient  to  prove 
what  they  are  expected  to  prove — is  almost  entirely  indifferent.  If  anything, 
the  greater  number  of  axioms  is  preferable,  for  this  may  show  a  finer  analysis; 
but  this  does  not  appear  to  be  necessarily  the  case.  There  is  a  good  deal  of 
popular  misunderstanding  on  this  point,  because  of  the  fact  that  so  much 
endeavor  has  been  directed  by  mathematicians  upon  the  elimination  of  super- 
fluous axioms — axioms  that  could  really  be  proved  from  the  remaining 
assumptions.  It  needs  to  be  clearly  understood  that  if  none  of  the  axioms 
of  a  given  set  is  superfluous — if  they  are  all  mutually  independent — their 
number  is,  generally  speaking,  a  matter  of  no  importance. 

'•'  To  be  perfectly  precise,  one  must  admit  the  limiting  case  in  which  the 
"pair"  consists  of  but  one  and  the  same  point  "twice  considered."  This, 
however,  is  a  topic  that  belongs  to  general  logic.  The  pair  "A  and  B"  may 
there  be  defined  as  the  class  (or  collection)  of  which  A  is  a  member  and  B 
in  a  member,  and  which  has  no  other  members.  It  is  not  specified,  and  it  is 
not  implied,  that  A  and  B  must  be  distinct. 

The  classical  geometry  conceived  of  this  limiting  case  in  a  characteristically 
different  way.  Instead  of  "considering  the  same  point  twice  over,"  it 
admitted  coincident  points.  There  is  no  reason  why  we  today  should  not  adopt 
a  similar  procedure;  and  for  the  purposes  of  this  study  there  would  be  some 
advantages  in  doing  so.  I  have  preferred,  however,  to  conform  to  the  pre- 
vailing fashion  as  far  as  possible. 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  401 

than."  There  are  several  reasons  for  preferring  the  latter,  of 
which  only  one  is  strictly  pertinent  in  this  place;  namely,  that  the 
choice  of  the  former  amounts  to  practically  the  same  thing  as  the 
assumption  of  distance  itself  as  an  indefinable  class  of  relations.10 

One  other  reason,  however,  is  of  too  great  methodological  im- 
portance to  be  denied  mention.  The  assertion  of  a  relation  such  as 
"to  be  just  as  far  apart  as"  is  generally  based,  not  on  positive  evi- 
dence, but  on  the  absence  of  negative  evidence.  If  we  are  dealing 
with  physical  objects,  and  A  and  B  are  farther  apart  than  C  and 
D,  we  can  in  many  instances  attest  this  fact  with  a  high  degree  of 
assurance.  As,  however,  this  relation  approaches  the  condition 
where  A  and  B  are  just  as  far  apart  as  C  and  D,  the  certainty  of 
our  judgment  decreases ;  and  a  condition  is  finally  reached  where  all 
that  we  can  say  is  that  we  see  no  further  difference.  Generally 
speaking,  propositions  asserting  the  relation  "to  be  farther  apart 
than"  are  of  a  higher  degree  of  probability  than  those  asserting 
the  relation  "to  be  just  as  far  apart  as."  What,  therefore,  the 
proposition,  that  A  and  B  are  just  as  far  apart  as  C  and  D,  actually 
means  in  the  system  of  science  is  that,  within  the  limits  of  our  ob- 
servation, A  and  B  are  not  farther  apart  than  C  and  D,  and  C  and 
D  are  not  farther  apart  than  A  and  B. 

It  is  very  striking,  how,  when  the  relation,  "to  be  farther  apart 
than, ' '  is  taken  as  fundamental,  the  difficulties  dwindle  away.  This 
can  best  be  shown  by  exhibiting  a  specimen  series  of  definitions. 
It  is  true  that,  from  the  mathematical  standpoint,  the  definitions 
that  occur  in  mathematics  are  matters  of  merely  verbal  signifi- 
cance. They  are  statements  that  certain  newly  presented  symbols 
may,  at  will,  be  substituted  for  certain  combinations  of  previously 
presented  symbols.  Nevertheless,  it  is  in  the  definitions  that  the 
analysis  of  the  complex  subject-matter  of  the  science  most  clearly 
appears. 

The  series  of  definitions  given  in  the  following  pages  extends 
as  far  as  the  introduction  of  the  notions  which  are  fundamental  to 
projective  and  descriptive  geometry.  Farther  than  that  we  need 
not  go;  for  the  "defining-value"  of  these  notions  is  well  known, 
and  that  of  our  own  indefinables  will  have  been  shown  to  be  at  least 

!0  It  may  be  recalled  that  in  Professor  Veblen  's  well-known  account  of 
the  foundations  of  elementary  geometry  two  indefinable  relations  are  em- 
ployed. In  addition  to  the  relation  of  congruence,  which  is  essentially  the  same 
as  "to  be  just  as  far  apart  as,"  he  introduces  the  relation  of  order  between 
three  points,  which  is  essentially  the  same  as  the  between-relation.  (I  say 
"essentially,"  because  in  each  case  there  may  be  an  unimportant  technical 
difference.)  The  resulting  system  is,  therefore,  not  purely  metrical,  but  is  a 
mixture  of  metrical  and  descriptive  elements;  and  it  labors  under  the  disad- 
vantage which  was  pointed  out  in  a  previous  note. 


402  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

as  great.  Our  task,  then,  will  be  to  make  clear  what,  from  the 
metrical  standpoint,  is  meant  by  the  order  of  points  in  a  straight 
line. 

INDEFINABLE^ 

I.  Point. 

II.  To  be  farther  apart  than. 

Points  are  to  be  represented  by  capital  letters.  Different  letters 
need  not  indicate  distinct  points. 

DEFINITIONS 

I.  If  A  and  B  are  not  farther  apart  than  C  and  D,  and  C  and 
D  are  not  farther  apart  than  A  and  B,  then  A  and  B  are  said  to  be 
just  as  far  apart  as  C  and  D. 

II.  The  distance  AB  is  the  class  of  pairs  of  points  that  are  just 
as  far  apart  as  A  and  B.     . 

This  definition  calls  for  some  comment.  Instead  of  defining  a 
distance  as  a  class  of  pairs  of  points,  we  might  define  it  as  the  dis- 
tinguishing property  of  that  class.  That  is  to  say,  we  might  define 
the  distance  AB  as  the  property  of  being  just  as  far  apart  as  A 
and  B.  This  would  be  in  closer  accord  with  our  common-sense  no- 
tion of  distance.  But,  as  students  of  logic  well  know,  propositions 
about  classes,  and  propositions  about  the  distinguishing  properties 
of  classes,  run  parallel  to  each  other.  The  two  sorts  of  proposi- 
tions represent  two  different  ways  of  regarding  the  same  facts — in 
extension  and  in  intension,  to  use  the  traditional  terms.  It  is  the 
general  custom  of  mathematicians  to  prefer  the  extensive  treatment ; 
and  there  is  no  reason  why  we  should  do  otherwise. 

The  definition  of  a  distance  as  a  class  has  this  consequence: 
that  we  shall  have  to  speak  of  the  same  distance,  not  of  equal  (or 
equivalent)  distances.  According  to  our  definition,  if  A  and  B  are 
just  as  far  apart  as  C  and  D,  the  distance  AB  and  the  distance  CD 
are  identical.  If  we  had  chosen  to  define  a  distance  as  a  property, 
the  case  would  be  different.  The  property  of  being  just  as  far  apart 
as  A  and  B  is  not  identical  with  the  property  of  being  just  as  far 
apart  as  C  and  D.  The  relation  between  these  properties  is  that 
they  imply  each  other,  or  are  equivalent. 

It  is  further  to  be  remarked  that  the  distance  AB  may  be  de- 
fined as  the  (symmetrical)  relation  subsisting  between  two  points, 
by  reason  of  the  fact  that  they  are  just  as  far  apart  as  the  points  A 
and  B.  This  definition  has  nothing  in  particular  to  recommend  it. 
But  it  is  worth  while  to  reflect  upon  it  a  little,  because  of  the  way 
in  which  it  brings  to  the  surface  the  unfitness  of  the  two-term  dis- 
tance relation  to  serve  as  one  of  the  bases  of  geometry- 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  403 

III.  If  A  and  B  are  farther  apart  than  C  and  D,  the  distance 
AB  is  said  to  be  greater  than  the  distance  CD. 

Here  it  is  to  be  observed  that  the  phrase  "to  be  greater  than" 
is  defined  in  a  particular  technical  sense:  namely,  as  it  is  applied 
to  distances.  In  arithmetic  a  relation  having  the  same  name  is  de- 
fined with  reference  to  real  numbers ;  and  it  is  one  of  the  first  tasks 
of  metrical  geometry  to  justify  this  ambiguous  use  of  the  words  by 
showing  that  its  own  greater-than  relation  has  the  same  formal 
properties  as  the  arithmetical  relation.  For  it  is  on  this  identity  of 
the  formal  properties  of  the  arithmetical  and  the  geometrical  greater- 
than,  that  the  theory  of  spatial  measurement  rests. 

IV.  The    distances    AB,    CD,*  « 
and  EF  are  said  to  be  compatible,  •  • 

if  there  exist  the  points,  X,  Y,  and  C  $ 

Z,  such  that  XY  is  the  same  as  -. 

AB,  YZ  is  the  same  as  CD,  and  '  ' 

XZ  is  the  same  as  EF. 

This  notion  of  compatibility  is  V  Z 

the  only  one  in  the  present  set  that  is  not  familiar  to  common  sense. 
We  do  not  absolutely  need  it  here,  and  it  is  introduced  only  be- 
cause it  enables  us  to  define  in  relatively  simple  terms  what  is 
meant  by  the  sum  of  two  distances. 

V.  The  sum  of  the  distances  AB  and  CD  is  a  distance  compatible 
with  them,  and  greater  than  any  other  such  distance  if  such  there 
be. 

In  the  figure  let  BV,  BW, 
BX,  BY,  and  BZ  all  be  the 
same  as  CD.  Then  (by  Defini- 
tion IV)  AV,  AW,  AX,  AY, 
and  AZ  are  all  compatible  with 
AB  and  CD.  One  of  the  five, 
namely  AX,  is  greater  than  any 
of  the  others;  and  it  is,  in  fact, 
greater  than  any  other  distance 
compatible  with  AB  and  CD.  "We  call  it  the  sum  of  AB  and  CD. 
Here  we  must  make  the  same  remark  about  the  use  of  the  term 
"sum"  that  was  made  above  with  regard  to  the  term  "greater 
than."  From  arithmetic  we  know  what  the  "sum"  of  two  real 
numbers  means.  Metrical  geometry  has  to  show  that  the  sum  of 
two  distances  has  the  same  formal  properties  that  belong  to  the 
sum  of  two  real  numbers.  This  is  very  easily  accomplished. 

VI.  If  A,  B,  and  C  are  distinct,  and  AC  is  the  sum  of  AB  and 
BC,  B  is  said  to  be  between  A  and  C. 


404  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

VII.  If  either  A  is  between  It  and  C,  or  B  is  between  A  and  C, 
or  C  is  between  A  and  B/  .4,  JS,  and  C  are  said  to  be  collinear. 

VIII.  The  straight  line  AB  is  the  class  of  points  collinear  with 
A  and  B,  together  with  A  and  B. 

Attention  must  now  be  called  to  a  few  characteristics  of  this 
series  of  definitions.  In  the  first  place,  the  definitions  are  exceed- 
ingly simple.  If  the  reader  will  glance  over  the  whole  series  of 
eight,  he  will  see  that  they  follow  one  upon  another  in  the  most 
natural  and  obvious  fashion.  When  once  the  proper  indefinables 
are  chosen,  the  definitions  are  almost  inevitable — not  because  others 
to  take  their  place  can  not  be  found,"  but  because  it  would  require 
a  good  deal  of  ingenuity  or  of  industry  to  think  of  them,  while 
these  fairly  suggest  themselves.  The  only  feature  that  smacks  in  the 
least  of  artificiality  is  the  notion  of  "compatibility,"  and  that  only 
on  account  of  the  novel  term  that  is  used.  The  problem  was,  how  to 
combine  two  distances  so  as  to  get  their  sum.  Is  not  the  obvious 
answer  that  the  outside  points  shall  be  as  far  apart  as  possible? 
At  any  rate,  if  the  definitions  are  not  inevitable,  they  are  at  least 
easy — so  easy  that  the  whole  set  can  be  grasped  by  the  mind  almost 
without  effort,  in  a  single  movement  of  the  attention. 

If  the  reader  has  studied  protective  geometry,  and  in  particular 
the  projective  definition  of  distance,  he  will  not  hesitate  to  admit 
that  the  metrical  definition  of  collinearity  is  incomparably  simpler. 

11  An  example  of  an  alternative  method  ia  suggested  by  Professor  C.  V. 
Huntington,  in  Mathematische  Annalen,  Vol.  73,  pp.  529f.  Professor  Huntington 
takes  as  his  indefinables  "sphere"  and  "is  contained  in."  A  "point"  is  de- 
nned as  a  sphere  in  which  no  other  sphere  is  contained.  "The  point  B  lies 
between  the  points  A  and  C,"  is  then  explained  as  meaning:  No  sphere  Z 
exists,  in  which  A  and  C  are  contained,  but  not  B. 

In  terms  of  our  own  indefinables,  a  sphere  is  a  class  of  points  whose  distance 
from  a  certain  point  is  not  greater  than  a  certain  distance.  For  one  sphere 
to  be  contained  in  another,  means  that  every  point  of  the  former  is  a  point 
of  the  latter.  Accordingly,  Professor  Huntington 's  definition  of  the  between- 
relation  becomes:  No  point  X  exists  such  that  there  exists  a  distance  TZ, 
such  that  BX  is  greater  than  YZ,  and  neither  AX  nor  CX  is  greater  than  YZ, 
This  is  obviously  more  complex  than  is  necessary ;  so  we  may  put  it :  No  X  exists, 
such  that  BX  is  greater  than  both  AX  and  CX. 

Professor  Huntington 's  device  suggests  others  that  to  him,  with  his  peculiar 
indefinables,  were  not  available.  For  example,  "  B  is  between  A  and  C ' '  may  be 
explained:  If  X  exists  such  that  AX  is  the  same  as  CX,  this  distance  is  greater 
than  BX.  Or  we  may  first  explain  "A,  B,  and  C  are  collinear"  as  meaning: 
No  X  exists  such  that  AX,  BX,  and  CX  are  the  same.  And  we  may  then  dis- 
tinguish the  outer  points,  say  by  their  greater  distance  from  each  other. 

In  any  case,  we  may  proceed  to  explain  "AB  is  the  sum  of  CD  and  EF" 
as  meaning:  X  exists  such  that  it  is  between  A  and  B,  and  AX  is  the  same  as 
CD,  and  BX  is  the  same  as  EF. 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  405 

In  the  second  place,  the  definitions  imply  nothing  as  to  the  num- 
ber of  dimensions  in  space.  Space  may  equally  well  have  one,  two, 
three,  or  more  dimensions,  and  these  definitions  will  still  hold  good. 
Substitute  the  word  ''instant"  for  "point,"  and  "interval"  for 
"distance,"  and  drop  the  last  two  definitions  as  superfluous,  and 
the  account  applies  perfectly  to  time.  The  like  is  true  of  the  metri- 
cal principles  which  we  shall  shortly  have  to  consider:  they  are  all 
equally  applicable  to  space  of  any  number  of  dimensions. 

It  has  sometimes  been  held  by  mathematicians  that  projective, 
descriptive,  and  metrical  geometry  presuppose  one  another  in  that 
order:  that  projective  geometry  is  logically  prior  to  descriptive  ge- 
ometry, and  both  of  these  to  metrical  geometry.  Logicians,  of 
course,  are  not  at  present  inclined  to  take  much  stock  in  the  notion 
of  logical  priority,  except  as  it  is  conceived  with  reference  to  some 
particular  deductive  system.  It  has  been  found  that  there  is  a  sur- 
prising amount  of  freedom  in  the  choice  of  indefinable  terms  and 
indemonstrable  propositions — how  much  we  do  not  know.  What  is 
logically  prior  in  one  construction  may  be  logically  posterior  in  an- 
other. Of  an  absolute  order  of  priority  we  know  nothing. 

But  for  our  present  purpose,  since  we  have  in  view  an  inquiry 
into  empirical  foundations,  the  really  important  question  of  prior- 
ity as  between  the  three  types  of  geometry  is  as  to  which  gives  the 
simplest  conception  of  the  nature  of  space.  In  this  respect,  metrical 
geometry  has  an  incontestable  and  enormous  advantage.  The  di- 
rection taken  by  the  history  of  the  science  is  here  the  path  of  least 
resistance.  Starting  from  the  theory  of  spatial  measurement,  we 
find  spatial  order  comparatively  easy  to  understand.  Starting  from 
the  arrangement  of  points  in  lines,  we  find  spatial  measurement  an 
intrinsically  and  unavoidably  abstruse  subject. 

Our  first  task  is  accomplished.  We  have  seen  what,  in  metrical 
terms,  a  linear  order  means.  But  the  meaning  of  our  assumed  in- 
definables  is  itself  set  forth  in  the  postulates  which  we  adopt,  and 
becomes  more  and  more  explicit  as  the  consequences  of  these  postu- 
lates are  successively  unfolded,  that  is  to  say,  as  the  system  of  ge- 
ometry is  constructed.  It  is  far  beyond  the  purpose  of  the  present 
study  to  attempt  the  construction  of  even  the  foundations  of  a  ge- 
ometry. It  is,  indeed,  not  difficult  to  set  forth  a  list  of  principles — 
only  about  sixteen  are  needed — from  which  the  Euclidean  geometry 
can  be  deduced.  But  to  provide  and  insure  the  mutual  independ- 
ence of  the  principles,  so  that  they  may  serve  as  the  postulates  of 
a  mathematical  system,  is  a  task  calling  for  a  very  special  com- 
petence and  training. 

However,  I  have  thought  it  well  to  present  in  this  place  a  state- 


406  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ment  of  certain  metrical  principles,  which,  so  far  as  they  go,  are 
independent  of  one  another,  and  which  are  sufficient  as  premises  for 
the  demonstration  of  the  most  important  properties  of  the  between- 
relation.  I  trust  that  they  will  be  of  service  in  throwing  light  upon 
the  empirical  considerations  that  are  to  follow." 

Points,  as  before,  are  denoted  by  capital  letters,  and  different 
letters  need  not  indicate  distinct  points. 

I.  If  A  and  B  are  farther  apart  than  C  and  D,  C  and  D  are  not 
farther  apart  than  A  and  B. 

In  other  words,  "to  be  farther  apart  than"  is  an  asymmetrical 
relation. 

II.  If  A  and  B  are  farther  apart  than  C  and  D,  and  E  and  F  are 
not  farther  apart  than  C  and  D,  A  and  B  are  farther  apart  than  E 
and  F. 

In  combination  with  the  preceding,  this  assures  us  that  if  A  and  B 
are  farther  apart  than  C  and  D,  and  if  C  and  D  are  farther  apart 
than  E  and  F,  A  and  B  are  farther  apart  than  E  and  F.  That  is 
to  say,  "to  be  farther  apart  than"  is  a  transitive  relation. 

It  also  follows  that  the  relation  "to  be  just  as  far  apart  as"  is 
transitive. 

III.  If  A  is  not  identical  with  B,  then,  for  all  values  of  X,  the 
distances  AB  and  XX  are  distinct. 

This  is  used  in  demonstrating  the  proposition  that  the  distance 
XX  is  constant,  and  is  in  fact  the  zero-distance;  that  is  to  say,  that 
if  XX  be  added  to  any  distance  YZ,  the  sum  is  YZ. 

IV.  If  A,  B,  C,  and  D  be  each  any  point,  X  exists  such  that  BX 
is  identical  with  CD,  and  AX  is  the  sum  of  AB  and  CD. 

This  assures  us  that  any  distance  and  any  distance  have  a  sum. 
It  also  assures  us  of  a  part  of  what  we  mean  by  the  "uniformity" 
of  space. 

V.  If  AC  is  greater  than  AD,  and  BC  is  the  sum  of  BA  and  AC, 
BC  is  greater  than  BD. 

From  this  it  follows  that  if  AC  is  greater  than  AD,  and  XY  is 
any  distance,  the  sum  of  AC  and  XY  is  greater  than  the  sum  of  AD 
andZY. 

VI.  If  A  and  B  are  not  identical,  and  if  BC  is  not  greater  than 
BD;  and  if  AD  is  the  sum  of  AB  and  BD,  and  if  AC  is  the  sum  of 
AB  and  BC;  then  BD  is  the  sum  of  BC  and  CD. 

This  provides  that  any  two  distances  shall  have  a  difference.  The 
last  three  principles,  or  their  equivalents,  are  necessary  to  show  that 

"It  should  be  remembered  that  we  assume  from  general  logic  that  the 
relation  of  co-membership  in  a  pair  is  symmetrical  with  respect  to  the  two 
members.  Accordingly  we  assume  without  question  that  "the  point  A  and  the 
point  B"  means  the  same  pair  as  "the  point  B  and  the  point  A." 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  407 

the  relation  "to  be  greater  than"  is  strictly  analogous  to  the  greater- 
than  relation  between  real  numbers. 

Assuming  these  six  principles  to  be  true,  we  can  easily  prove  the 
associative  law  for  the  addition  of  distances.  (The  commutative  law 
is  in  this  system  a  mere  identity.)  We  can  also  prove  the  following 
series  of  propositions  (using  the  expression  (XYZ)  to  mean  " Y  is  be- 
tween X  and  Z")  : 

(i)  If  (ABX)  and  (AST),  and  EX  is  identical  with  BY,  X 
is  identical  with  Y. 

(ii)  If  (ABX)  and  (ABY),  and  BY  is  greater  than  BX,  then 
(BXY)  and  (AXY). 

(iii)  If  (AXB)  and  (AYB),  and  AX  is  identical  with  AY,  X  is 
identical  with  Y. 

(iv)  If  (AXB)  and  (AYB),  and  AY  is  greater  than  AX,  then 
(AXY)  and  (XYB). 

(v)    If  (XAB)  and  (ABY),  then  (XAT)  and  (XBT). 

(vi)  If  (AXB)  and  (ABY),  then  (AXY)  and  (XBY). 
And  from  these  six  propositions  we  may  derive  the  following  generali- 
zation, which  establishes  the  complete  determination  of  the  straight 
line  by  any  two  of  its  points : 

If  A,  B,  C,  and  D  are  distinct,  and  if  A,  B,  and  C  are  collinear 
and  A,  B,  and  D  are  collinear,  then  A,  C,  and  Z>  are  eollinear. 

THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA. 

BKYN  MAWE  COLLEGE. 


A  METAPHYSICIAN'S  PETITIO 

OF  those  who  interest  themselves  to-day  in  the  general  problem 
of  the  method  of  experience,  the  greater  number  approach 
the  subject  in  the  light  of  experience  alone.  That  is  to  say,  they 
criticize  experience  without  a  priori  presuppositions  as  to  its  na- 
ture. For  example,  they  observe  the  processes  of  scientific  investi- 
gation as  a  parent  observes  the  breathing  of  her  child  or  a  physi- 
ologist the  functions  of  the  brain.  They  examine  the  industrial  and 
commercial  activities  of  human  beings,  their  political  strategies 
and  recreative  sports,  with  the  meticulous  care  of  a  psychologist 
interested  in  the  phenomenon  of  fatigue.  The  artistic  tastes,  the 
religious  rituals  and  the  poetic  creations  of  people  are  as  interest- 
ing to  the  methodologist  as  the  process  of  metabolism  to  a  biologist. 
Above  all  he  hugs  to  his  bosom  the  transformations  of  attitude  and 
emotion  through  which  reflective  life  passes  out  of  one  and  into 
another  of  these  phases  of  experience,  believing  that  therein  espe- 
cially is  ultimately  to  be  found  the  synthesis  that  endows  civilization 


408  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

with  integrity,  the  filament  of  spirituality  that  binds  together  the 
associated  life  of  the  world. 

The  methodologist  postulates  nothing  but  this  teeming  life,  and 
that  he  approaches  on  his  knees,  as  becomes  the  student  of  it.  He 
does  not  pretend  to  know  a  priori  that  it  is  all  a  symphony  played 
on  the  motifs  of  matter  and  mind:  neither  does  he  presume  to 
know  prior  to  observing  the  fact  that  it  is  not:  he  will  see  what  he 
shall  see,  and  to  report  what  he  has  found  he  will  use  whatever 
conception-aids  the  subject  beautifully  fits  as  a  glove  fits  the  hand. 

What  he  everywhere  finds  is  customs  and  the  straining  of  strong 
men  to  alter  them,  an  act  that  is  both  habitual  and  accommodative, 
or  rather  a  system  of  such  acts  rooted  in  the  past  and  moving  for- 
ward into  an  as  yet  problematical  future.  Nowhere  does  he  find 
absolute  gaps  in  the  moving  whole :  on  the  contrary,  human  experi- 
ence appears  to  be  a  processional  continuum.  Individuals  succeed, 
or  they  fail,  in  utter  obliviousness  to  the  disparity  between  a  sub- 
stance that  thinks  and  another  that  is  extended.  If  one's  hates  are 
accompanied  by  right-hand  spiral  motions  of  the  molecules  of  his 
brain  and  his  loves  by  left-hand  spiral  motions,  the  whirligigs  are 
amusing  only;  one  is  intent  on  his  objectives,  alike  whether  these 
be  material  or  spiritual. 

The  methodologist  notes  these  facts,  and  he  too  feels  indifferent 
to  metaphysical  dualisms.  What  abstractions,  however  hoary,  can 
compare  in  fascination  with  the  youth  and  vigor,  the  concrete  rich- 
ness and  teeming  verve  of  life's  artistry?  In  reporting  his  find- 
ings, the  methodologist  must  use  the  language  of  logic,  psychology 
and  perhaps  cosmology ;  but  when  he  speaks  of  bodies  he  is  think- 
ing of  a  system  of  habitual  activities  in  process  of  reformation; 
when  he  speaks  of  consciousness  he  is  thinking  of  the  moment  of 
reformation  itself;  when  he  refers  to  objects  he  has  in  mind  con- 
trolling contents  of  present  experience  that  mean  something  not 
now  existent  but  interesting  and  to  be  experienced;  when  he  men- 
tions the  future  he  probably  has  in  mind  in  most  instances,  not 
some  distant  thing  that  does  not  now  exist,  but  the  present  experi- 
ence of  expectation  and  purpose  that  characterizes  all  real  know- 
ing. Datum  and  ideatum  are  not  for  him  pebbles  in  the  loaf  of 
experience  but  moments  in  a  continuous  process. 

Now  comes  one  with  a  metaphysic.  "Ah,"  he  notes,  "Method- 
ologist speaks  of  present  body  and  of  past  or  future  existences  that 
are  not  present  at  all.  He  is  therefore  a  dualist,  probably  an  in- 
teractionist  that  knows  not  his  own  mind."  Or,  "He  denies  the 
existence  of  what  I  call  consciousness.  He  is  therefore  a  materialist 
ashamed  of  himself,  a  materialist  ashamed  to  accept  the  implica- 


A  METAPHYSICIAN'S  PET  IT  10  409 

tions  of  his  own  language."  Mr.  Lovejoy  thus  finds  pragmatism 
materialistic.  We  do  not  presume  to  speak  for  all  pragmatists: 
just  possibly  some  of  them  would  not  assent  to  our  present  thesis: 
but  the  theory  of  knowledge  of  which  Dewey  and  his  pupils  are 
the  living  exponents  in  this  country  is  fundamentally  a  method- 
ology, not  a  metaphysic,  and  reading  metaphysical  meanings  into 
their  words  is  a  petitio  of  obvious  character. 

In  an  article  in  this  JOURNAL  (Vol.  XIX,  p.  6),  Lovejoy  is  reply- 
ing to  an  article  of  Bode  and  quotes  from  the  latter,  "A  careful 
inventory  of  our  assets  brings  to  light  no  such  entities  as  those 
which  have  been  placed  to  our  credit.  We  do  not  find  body  and 
object  and  consciousness,  but  only  body  and  object."  We  may  sup- 
pose Bode's  meaning  to  be,  "We  find  only  organized  habitual  re- 
sponses in  process  of  reformation  and  a  controlling  content  of  pres- 
ent experience  that  means  something-to-be-found-or-achieved."  By 
way  of  criticism  Mr.  Lovejoy  solemnly  warns  the  reader  that  this 
is  materialism  and  proceeds  to  refute  materialism  by  observing, 
"Upon  the  materialistic  hypothesis  practical  reflection  itself  is  noth- 
ing but  a  motion  of  matter;  if  'bodies  and  (physical)  objects'  are 
the  only  factors  involved  in  'intelligence,'  it  should  be  possible  to 
describe  the  phenomenon  called  'planning'  wholly  in  physical  terms 
— i.e.,  in  terms  of  masses  actually  existing,  of  positions  actually 
occupied,  of  molar  or  molecular  movements  actually  occurring,  at 
the  time  when  the  planning  is  taking  place." 

Thus  by  following  the  association  of  ideas  in  his  own  mind,  by 
jumping  with  certain  associations  of  the  word  "body,"  the  meta- 
physician passes  out  of  the  universe  of  pragmatic  methodology  into 
the  universe  of  mechanistic  cosmology  with  an  alacrity  as  amazing  as 
it  is  alogical.  Incidentally,  let  it  be  noted,  as  evidence  of  Mr.  Love- 
joy's  desire  that  the  reader  shall  follow  him  closely,  that  the  word 
"(physical)"  in  parenthesis  is  not  in  the  original  text  of  Bode's 
article  at  all. 

Again,  we  read  on  page  seven  of  Mr.  Lovejoy 's  article,  "Thus 
in  fixing  his  attention  especially  upon  'intelligence'  in  its  practical 
aspect,  the  pragmatist  is  brought  face  to  face  with  that  type  of  ex- 
perience in  which  the  empirical  presence  of  non-physical  entities 
and  processes  is,  perhaps,  more  plainly  evident  than  in  any  other. ' ' 
If  Mr.  Lovejoy  had  written,  "that  type  of  experience  in  which  the 
empirical  presence  of  what  a  certain  metaphysical  dualist  regards 
as  non-physical  entities  and  processes,"  we  should  have  no  reason 
to  complain  of  his  logic ;  but  in  that  case  there  would  have  been  no 
point  to  his  criticism.  Again,  on  page  seven,  "He  (the  pragmatist) 
is  primarily  interested,  not  in  the  question  how  we  can  know  an 


410  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

external,  coexistent  object,  but  in  the  question  how  one  moment  of 
experience  can  know  and  prepare  for  another  moment.  It  is  in 
short  to  what  I  have  elsewhere  named  Intel-temporal  cognitions  that 
his  analysis  is  devoted;  it  is  by  man's  habit  of  looking  before  and 
after  that  he  is  chiefly  impressed.  Now  to  look  before  and  after  is — 
as  my  previous  paper  pointed  out — to  behold  the  physically  non- 
existent." 

As  a  matter  of  fact,  intertemporal  cognition,  as  Mr.  Lovejoy 
means  the  phrase,  is  not  at  all  what  the  methodologist  is  supremely 
interested  in.  Intertemporal  cognition  is  cognition  of  a  specific 
type,  such  as,  "Yesterday  I  made  an  engagement  that  I  shall  ful- 
fill tomorrow";  and  the  methodologist  is  far  from  being  so  naive 
and  inconsequential  as  to  say  that  all  intelligence  is  cognition  of  this 
type.  On  the  contrary  his  conception  of  cognition  holds  true  of 
this  type  of  cognitions,  if  it  holds  at  all ;  and  Lovejoy  simply  begs 
the  question  he  is  ostensibly  discussing  when  he  thus  states,  or  pre- 
tends to  state,  the  methodologist 's  doctrine.  What  the  latter  is 
emphasizing  is  a  fact  noted,  we  believe,  by  every  good  book  on 
psychology  written  within  the  last  forty  years,  viz.,  the  fact  that  all 
cognitive  activities  are  teleological  functions.  Lest  anyone  con- 
strue teleology  transcendentally,  as  has  been  done  so  often,  the 
methodologist  describes  teleology  in  terms  of  actual  experience,  and 
that  involves  mention  of  the  time  consumed  by  any  process  or 
function  of  actual  experience.  There  exists,  however,  a  vast  differ- 
ence between  the  time  consumed  by  a  cognitive  function  and  the 
time  content  of  intertemporal  cognitions,  a  difference  that  every 
psychologist  recognizes.  The  former  is  part  of  the  form  of  cogni- 
tion in  general,  the  latter  is  content  in  a  specific  class  of  cognitions. 
Mr.  Lovejoy  confuses  the  specific  cognition  of  temporal  relations, 
the  habit  of  looking  before  and  after,  with  the  prospective,  purpo- 
sive character  of  all  cognition. 

Of  course  the  methodologist  means  that  temporal  cognition  is 
as  purposive  as  any  other  type  of  cognition.  Observation  of  the 
time  cognitions  of  small  children  has  convinced  the  present  writer 
that  the  child's  first  experience  of  time  relations  is  his  experience 
of  enforced  waiting  while  his  nurse  is  coming  to  relieve  his  discom- 
fort or  bring  him  food.  Especially  when  he  wakens  before  the  time 
for  his  feeding,  and  lies  there  suffering  while  the  hands  of  the  clock 
move  slowly  to  the  hour,  he  is  becoming  conscious  of  duration. 
When  children  first  begin  to  talk,  their  judgments  of  futurity  take 
on  a  semblance  of  accuracy  and  completeness  months  before  their 
judgments  of  pastness  do.  Tomorrow's  picnic  excursion  and  the 
experiences  of  next  Sunday,  when  the  little  one  will  be  taken  to 


A  METAPHYSICIAN 'S  PETITIO  411 

Sunday  School,  are  fairly  definite  concepts  long  before  he  has  any 
definite  idea  of  what  happened  yesterday;  and  it  is  most  interest- 
ing to  observe  how  very  slowly  the  conception  of  the  day  before 
yesterday  begins  to  function  in  his  experience.  From  the  very 
start  his  time  experience  is  thus  relative  to  his  needs  and  desires, 
while  clock-time,  the  time  of  the  mathematician,  the  even  flowing 
continuum  of  duration,  is  a  late  abstract  construction  of  social  ex- 
perience and  is  everywhere  relative  to  the  need  to  measure  or  other- 
wise conceive  time,  i.e.,  to  the  need  of  organizing  "the  present"  in 
a  conceptual  control  of  present  activity.  Quite  contrary  to  Mr. 
Lovejoy's  assertion,  we  should  say  the  pragmatist  is  logically  com- 
mitted to  a  more  continuous  and  profound  interest  in  the  past  than 
is  any  other  living  philosopher.  For  history  is  a  study  of  "how 
man  came  to  be  as  he  is  and  believe  as  he  does, ' ' 1  while  conceptions 
of  what  man  is  and  believes  are  thoroughly  teleological.  An  his- 
torical consciousness,  a  consciousness  that  history  is  here  and  now 
in  process  of  being  made,  is  the  first  essential  of  intelligence.  It 
is  the  first  prerequisite  of  effective  participation  in  community 
life.  Such  is  the  pragmatist 's  emphasis  on  knowledge  of  the  past. 

Mr.  Lovejoy  finds  that  Bode,  whose  article  is  in  part  a  reply  to 
an  earlier  one  of  Lovejoy  himself,  does  not  stick  to  the  point. 
"Throughout  most  of  his  paper,  then,  Professor  Bode,  instead  of 
looking  at  the  evidence  offered  for  this  conclusion,  which  he  osten- 
sibly rejects,  appears  to  fix  his  gaze  on  another  object  altogether." 
No  wonder !  Two  men  standing  back  to  back  and  gazing  at  differ- 
ent points  on  the  horizon  say,  the  one,  "That  mountain  is  wooded 
to  the  top,"  and  the  other,  "No,  that  mountain  is  bald."  It  is 
amusing  to  read  in  Lovejoy's  article,  "After  careful  study  of  his 
paper,  I  remain  in  some  doubt  whether  he  holds  that  pragmatism 
implies  materialism  or  not."  He  need  not  be  in  doubt  as  to  this 
point,  for  Bode  distinctly  writes,  "The  question  what  is  real  is  ab- 
solutely sterile."  The  real  problem,  to  Bode,  is  the  problem  of 
method.  In  his  most  metaphysical  mood  he  would  probably  name 
his  doctrine  neither  idealism  nor  materialism,  neither  intellectual- 
ism  nor  empiricism.  He  would  probably  name  it  experiencism, — 
if  only  there  were  such  a  word.  As  for  realism,  if  that  can  be  said 
to  consist  in  treating  a  subject  matter  in  a  consistently  objective 
manner  without  a  priori  presuppositions,  he  is  a  realist.  However, 
as  a  science  of  the  method  of  experience  pragmatism  is  privileged 
to  abstract  from  the  problems  of  metaphysics,  except  as  the  meta- 
physician's own  method  of  procedure  presents  itself  as  a  problem. 

It  would  be  a  work  of  supererogation  to  trace  in  detail  the 

i  James  Harvey  Robinson. 


412  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

many  instances  of  this  fallacy  of  begging  the  question  in  Mr.  Love- 
joy's  Pragmatism  versus  the  Pragmatist,  an  essay  that  appeared  in 
a  volume  entitled  Critical  Realism.  Here,  however,  it  appears  in 
greater  variety  than  in  the  article  referred  to  above.  Here,  for  ex- 
ample, Mr.  Lovejoy  flings  question-begging  epithets  about  with 
redundant  profusion.  Here  the  rule  of  some  lawyers,  that  when 
you  have  no  case  it  is  good  to  abuse  the  opposing  counsel  or  their 
brief,  is  conscientiously  followed.  Here  a  fictitious  question  which 
is  in  fact  a  case  of  many  questions,  the  presumption  of  proposing 
to  decide  what  kind  of  a  metaphysician  the  pragmatist  is,  is  un- 
blushingly  propounded.  The  work  of  deliberately  trying  to  make 
the  pragmatist  say  things  he  never  meant  to  say,  of  trying  to  make 
him  say  things  that  Mr.  Lovejoy  thinks  he  ought  to  have  meant  to 
say,  and  of  then  pretending  to  evaluate  his  doctrine  by  the  ficti- 
tious and  often  fantastic  results,  is  here  arduously  pursued ;  but  it 
is  not  what  one  would  call  helpful  criticism.  It  is  as  futile  a  pro- 
cedure as  trying  to  decide  how  many  angels  can  skip  around  on  the 
point  of  a  pin. 

For  example,  on  page  46,  after  quoting  from  Dewey  a  state- 
ment of  the  pragmatist 's  notion  of  experience  as  "a  matter  of 
functions  and  habits,  of  active  adjustments  and  readjustments,  of 
coordinations  and  activities,  rather  than  of  states  of  consciousness, ' ' 
the  article  continues,  "Here  we  have  an  explanation  which  seems 
to  swing  our  interpretation  of  the  pragmatist 's  position  wholly  over 
to  the  realistic  side — and  indeed  to  the  neo-realistic  side.  He  ap- 
pears in  this  passage  as  an  ardent  adherent  of  what  has  been  named 
.  .  .  'pan-objectivism' — as  one  who  denies  the  existence  of  states 
of  consciousness  altogether."  As  if  the  words  of  Dewey  could  log- 
ically be  construed  to  be  a  denial  of  the  existence  of  states  of  con- 
sciousness in  the  pragmatist 's  sense  of  the  word!  As  if  indeed  the 
first  essayist  of  both  Studies  in  Logical  Theory  and  Creative  Intel- 
ligence meant  to  say  anything  of  the  kind!  Pan-objectivism  af- 
firmed one  term  of  a  traditional  epistemological  dualism,  that  of 
consciousness  and  the  object,  and  tried  to  deny  the  other  term, 
tardily  reckoning  with  the  fact  that,  the  terms  of  that  dualism  must 
be  accepted  or  rejected  together.  It  is  absurd  to  say  that  Mr. 
Dewey  is  doing  that,  and  yet  the  article  in  question  proceeds  for 
some  pages  in  a  fatuous  attempt  to  criticize  his  theory  as  though 
he  were.  We  can  be  sure  that  Dewey  rejects  Lovejoy 's  conception 
of  consciousness;  but  it  is  presumptuous  to  assert,  without  even  at- 
tempting to  state  the  pragmatist 's  conception,  that  that  is  a  denial 
of  the  existence  of  states  of  consciousness  altogether. 

The  confusion  already  referred  to  of  time- judgment  with  the 
prospective  and  purposive  character  of  all  judgment  is  even  more 


A  METAPHYSICIAN'S  PETITIO  413 

elaborate  in  the  article  we  are  now  discussing.  It  is  here  a  veri- 
table dust-cloud  enveloping  the  entire  argument.  "A  more  signifi- 
cant error,  and  one,  as  I  think  it  possible  to  show,  which  is  incon- 
sistent with  a  true  instrumentalist  logic,  is  Mr.  Dewey's  Limita- 
tion of  the  'knowledge-experience'  exclusively  to  forward-looking 
thoughts,"  (p.  52).  "This  formula  .  .  .  manifestly  tells  only  half 
the  story,  at  best.  It  ignores  the  patent  empirical  fact  that  many 
of  our  'meanings'  are  retrospective — and  the  specifically  'prag- 
matic' fact  that  such  meanings  are.  indispensable  in  the  planning  of 
action,"  (p.  53).  "The  pragnaatist  .  .  .  manifests  a  curious  aver- 
sion from  admitting  that  we  have  knowledge,  and  'true  knowledge,' 
about  the  past.  I  have  already  cited  from  Mr.  Dewey  a  formal 
definition  of  'knowledge'  which  excludes  from  the  denotation  of  the 
term  everything  except  judgments  of  anticipation"  (p.  63).  The 
citation  referred  to  is,  I  presume,  the  second  note  on  page  52.  But 
all  of  this  exposition  of  instrumentalistic  pragmatism  misrepresents 
its  subject,  owing  to  its  author's  failure  to  recognize  the  difference 
between  the  teleological  reference  and  effect  of  every  genuine  cogni- 
tion and  the  mathematical  time  in  which  it  transpires. 

An  illustration  may  make  the  matter  clear.  A  young  man  is 
at  work  in  the  same  room  with  me:  he  raises  his  head  and  looks 
about:  he  is  thinking,  as  indeed  I  am,  that  the  room  is  close:  he 
notes  that  the  windows  are  all  closed  and  opens  two  of  them.  He 
first  perceived  the  close  air  of  the  room,  a  cognitive  experience 
based  on  years  of  past  experience  in  similar  situations,  and  a  cogni- 
tive experience  that  meant  for  him  the  need  of  a  livelier  circula- 
tion of  air  in  the  room.  He  then  perceived  the  closed  windows- 
capable-of-being-opened,  rose  and  opened  two  of  them.  To  me, 
looking  on  sympathetically,  the  perception  of  the  close  air  led  to 
the  perception  that  windows  could  be  opened,  and  that,  in  turn, 
referred  to  events  about  to  be  affected  by  my  companion's  action. 
But  to  him  the  two  perceptions  were  simply  perceptions :  they  were 
through  and  through  purposive.  He  returned  to  his  chair  with  no 
consciousness  that  time  had  elapsed  since  his  attention  was  inter- 
rupted by  organic  sensations  of  stuffiness.  What  he  perceived  was 
(1)  the  close  air  of  the  room  and  (2)  the  windows  about  to  be 
opened ;  but  to  me,  looking  on,  both  perceptions  involved  memories 
of  the  past  and  ideas  of  the  future.  One  need  not,  unless  indeed 
he  will  to  do  so,  confuse  my  onlooker's  analysis  of  the  processes  of 
my  friend's  experience  with  the  actual  contents  of  those  experi- 
ences ;  and  any  one  who  wills  to  confuse  these  two  things  is  deliber- 
ately guilty  of  what  might  well  be  termed  the  metaphysician's  fal- 
lacy. If  such  an  one  reads  into  the  methodologist 's  description  of 


414  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

such  experiences  his  own  metaphysical  meanings,  he  is  guilty  of 
the  metaphysician's  petitio. 

Much  is  said  by  Mr.  Love  joy  about  Mr.  Dewey's  phrase  "pres- 
ent-as-absent "  for  the  purpose  of  convincing  the  reader  that  it 
denotes  a  time-cognition ;  but  no  student  of  the  psychology  of  time- 
cognition  is  convinced  by  these  many  animadversions.  The  term 
time-cognition  denotes  several  different  sorts  of  cognition.  At  the 
lowest  it  denotes  an  immediate  sense  of  duration,  of  interruption; 
(2)  it  denotes  the  cognition  of  intervals  or  periods  that  must  elapse 
ere  the  end  of  a  desire  is  attainable;  (3)  it  denotes  a  sense  of  the 
values  of  familiar  experiences  with  no  necessary  consciousness  of 
the  pastness  of  those  experiences;  (4)  it  denotes  an  explicit  con- 
sciousness of  intervals  of  past  experience;  and  (5)  it  denotes  the 
highly  abstract,  prodigiously  useful,  public  thing  which  we  have 
called  clock-time,  mathematical  time  with  its  evenly  flowing  con- 
tinuity marked  by  the  recurring  transits  of  a  star,  by  the  flow  of 
sand  in  an  hour  glass,  by  the  uniform  rate  of  motion  of  hands 
round  the  dial  of  a  clock,  by  the  mathematical  definition  of  continu- 
ous manifolds,  and  so  forth.  Until  the  metaphysical  critic  of  prag- 
matism recognizes  that  genuine  cognitions  may  involve  any  of  these 
meanings  of  the  term,  or  none  of  them,  his  criticisms  are  not  likely 
to  be  helpful  to  the  methodologist.  The  idea  that  psychology  has 
nothing  to  say  about  time-cognition  that  concerns  the  metaphysician 
or  the  epistemologist  is  so  deeply  embedded, — the  idea  that  psychol- 
ogy deals  solely  with  a  morass  of  subjectivity  that  philosophy  is 
too  pure  to  behold, — that  it  is  difficult  for  some  to  understand  the 
viewpoint  and  method  of  instrumentalism.  Mr.  Lovejoy  fails  to 
understand  not  only  Mr.  Dewey  but  the  whole  methodological  ap- 
proach to  the  problem  of  knowledge,  and  to  understand  that  ap- 
proach is,  by  your  leave,  the  first  indispensable  step  toward  a  real 
logic.  Mr.  Lovejoy  finds  the  pragmatist  to  be  a  subjective  idealist, 
a  pan-objectivist,  materialist,  a  dualistic  interactionist,  and  above 
all  an  errorist ;  but  the  reader  will  search  his  criticisms  in  vain  for 
even  an  approximately  adequate  exposition  of  the  doctrine  he  is 
discussing. 

G.  A.  TAWNEY. 
THB  UNIVERSITY  or  CINCINNATI. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Proceedings  of  the  Aristotelian  Society,  1920-1921.     New  Series, 
Vol.  XXI.    London :  Williams  and  Norgate.    Pp.  iv  +  246. 
Part  of  the  strength  of  the  excellent  series  of  papers  which  make 


BOOK  REVIEWS  415 

i 

up  the  present  volume  is  due  to  the  contributions  of  the  American 
delegates  to  the  Oxford  Congress.  Professor  W.  P.  Montague  pre- 
sented before  the  Aristotelian  Society  (meeting  of  December  6, 
1920)  a  paper  entitled  "Variation,  Heredity  and  Consciousness," 
embodying  suggestions  and  hypotheses  concerning  the  relation  of 
life  and  mind  to  the  realm  of  physical  energy.  He  calls  his  argu- 
ment "a  mechanist  answer  to  the  vitalist  challenge."  In  so  ob- 
scure a  field  any  hypothesis  is  worthy  of  a  trial,  provided  it  is  at 
all  capable  of  verification.  The  present  reviewer  finds  it  hard  to 
decide  whether  or  no  the  subtle  analogies  to  which  Professor 
Montague  appeals  do  present  sufficient  possibilities  of  verification. 
Thus  he  compares  biological  variation  to  vector  addition  in  me- 
chanics, which  gives  from  old  elements  a  sum  which  is  both  perti- 
nent and  novel.  It  is  a  pretty  analogy,  but  who  shall  say  whether 
it  is  more?  Furthermore,  vector  addition  has  already  itself  given 
certain  mechanistically  minded  students  of  physics  considerable  oc- 
casion for  perplexity,  as  for  instance,  addition  of  accelerations. 
And  certainly  the  mechanist  philosopher  with  a  single-track  mind 
would  be  a  bit  distressed  by  Professor  Montague's  remark  that 
"Nature  is  not  stone-blind  .  .  .  she  is  an  artist  who  works  as  she 
goes. ' '  The  next  analogy,  which  claims  indeed  to  be  a  full  identity, 
is  between  heredity  and  higher  space-time  derivatives,  accelerations 
of  accelerations.  The  comparison  is  said  to  illustrate  how  a  great 
complexity  of  promised  movement  can  be  resident  in  a  single  par- 
ticle, or  small  group  of  particles  of  matter,  which  group  is  at  the 
moment  apparently  quiescent,  like  an  upward  thrown  stone  at  the 
top  of  its  flight.  So  far  the  analogy  holds  good,  but  the  reviewer 
can  not  make  clear  to  himself  how  this  explains  anything  more 
about  heredity.  To  him,  the  very  conception  of  an  organism,  a 
real  unit  in  nature,  going  its  own  way,  not  merely  self-preservative, 
but  using,  and  in  a  measure  dominating,  its  environment,  seems  in- 
consistent with  strict  mechanism — though,  for  that  matter,  no  better 
explained  by  the  ineffable  mysteries  of  vitalism.  In  the  third  part 
of  the  paper,  Professor  Montague  again  takes  up,  in  modified  re- 
statement, his  earlier  identification  of  consciousness  with  potential 
energy,  an  identification,  it  must  be  said,  of  the  mysterious  with  the 
inscrutable.  Yet  the  comparisons  instituted  are  certainly  tantaliz- 
ing, and  leave  the  reader  wondering  whether  in  the  future  some 
new  road  of  investigation  may  not  open  up  through  this  region — 
for  it  is  a  matter  of  fact  that  there  are  relationships  of  some  sort 
between  energy  and  thinking,  and  Professor  Montague's  guess  is 
not  the  worst  that  has  been  made.  Nevertheless,  the  members  of 
the  Aristotelian  Society  may  well  have  been  left  with  a  state  of 


416  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

considerable  stress  and  confusion  inhabiting  their  own  tanks  of 
potential  energy  after  the  first  hearing  of  this  rather  bewildering 
paper. 

Professor  J.  E.  Boodin's  paper  on  "Cosmic  Evolution"  is  less 
disturbing  to  customary  ideas.  His  discussion  centers  about  the 
opinions  of  L.  J.  Henderson,  the  physiological  chemist  (e.g.,  his 
The  Fitness  of  the  Environment),  and  Henry  F.  Osborn,  the  biolo- 
gist (in  his  The  Origin  and  Evolution  of  Life).  But  back  of  this 
is  a  wider  philosophic  view :  ' '  We  must  learn  that  the  cosmos  is  the 
true  unit  of  reality,"  and  further,  "There  must  be  an  eternal 
hierarchy  of  levels  in  the  universe."  It  would  be  hard  to  dispute 
that  statements  so  general  were  not  in  some  sense  true. 

Professor  R.  F.  A.  Hoernle  might  perhaps  also  be  claimed  as  an 
American  contributor  to  this  volume.  His  "Plea  for  a  Phenome- 
nology of  Meaning"  will  receive  the  endorsement  of  all  students 
in  that  subtle  region.  The  reviewer  would  venture  to  suggest  that 
Charles  Peirce's  cryptic  classification  of  signs  may  best  be  inter- 
preted as:  (a)  indices,  or  using  what  is  naturally  conjoined  with 
another  as  the  sign  of  it,  as  palm-trees  in  the  desert  are  a  sign  of 
water;  (6)  icons,  or  signifying  through  resemblance,  as  a  portrait 
or  a  map;  and  (c)  signs  whose  original  nexus  with  the  thing  sym- 
bolized has  been  obscured  through  use,  so  that  the  relation  is  now 
arbitrary  and  so  needs  an  interpretant  "who  remembers  what  it 
meant."  I  point  with  my  finger,  it  is  an  index;  I  draw  a  picture  in 
the  air  to  convey  my  meaning,  it  is  an  icon — in  either  case  the  whole 
world  understands ;  I  speak  a  word,  it  is  what  Peirce  calls  a  symbol, 
and  only  my  own  people  can  interpret  me.  This  third  class  is 
doubtless  rather  ill  represented  by  the  word  "symbol."  Professor 
Hoernle  is  well  advised  in  again  calling  attention  to  the  distinction, 
so  notable  in  the  case  of  language,  between  the  indicative  and  the 
expressive  function  of  signs.1  Perhaps  the  third  class  above  could 
be  revised,  still  with  genuine  regard  to  Peirce's  own  intention,  to 
include  all  those  signs  whose  most  marked  characteristic  is  this 
marriage  of  expression  of  intent  and  designation  of  fact.  Lan- 
guage is  here  the  typical  case.  To  the  extent  to  which  the  dictum 
is  true — and  it  is  only  partly  true — that  "the  real  is  particular, 
but  thought  is  of  the  universal,"  this  third  class  is  also  the  marriage 
of  the  universal  and  particular.  Indices  move  in  the  realm  of  par- 
ticulars only.  You  can  make  general  statements  about  indices,  hut 
each  several  index  is,  as  such,  individual  and  unique  in  itself  and 

i  The  author  leaves  one  perplexed  whether  his  terminology  follows  Husserl 
or  Meinong  here  (p.  85,  note).  Surely  Meinong's  usage  is  preferable:  I  ex- 
press  my  own  opinions  and  feelings,  I  indicate  or  designate  an  external  fact — 
«nd  every  sentence  I  speak  does  both  at  once. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  417 

In  its  reference.  Icons  are  indeed  in  the  realm,  of  the  universal, 
for  a  portrait  designates  an  individual  only  in  so  far  as  that  indi- 
vidual has  ceased  to  be  unique  and  is  duplicated  in  the  portrait 
itself.  But  the  user  of  pictures  does  not  clearly  discriminate  the 
universal,  and  picture  language  or  imitative  gesture  is  therefore 
but  the  beginning  of  true  language.  In  true  language  the  universal 
and  the  particular  have  each  their  distinctive  part.  Every  diction- 
ary word  stands  for  a  universal,  yet  through  language  we  do  man- 
age to  discuss  the  particular  facts  of  this  particular  world  round 
about  us.  But  the  other  aspects  of  language  must  not  be  forgotten 
either,  if  we  are  to  have  an  adequate  theory.  Language  is,  as  Pro- 
fessor Hoernle  well  insists,  a  double  revelation;  my  language  is  a 
revelation  of  the  world  I  know,  but  also  it  is  a  revelation  of  me. 
On  the  other  hand,  let  us  not  forget  that  language  is  social,  it  is  a 
revelation  to  somebody  and  needs  an  interpreter.  It  brings  minds 
together,  but  it  leaves  them  curiously  isolated.  For  what  does  really 
pass  across?  Black  marks  visible  on  paper;  quiverings  of  the  air. 
Out  of  such  things  we  each  of  us,  a  lonely  worker,  build  a  world, 
wherein  we  nevertheless  meet  our  fellows  and  come  to  a  knowledge 
of  self  and  of  others.  Professor  Hoernle  is  right  in  saying  we  need 
to  study  these  queer  facts  more  closely. 

Perhaps  the  reviewer,  through  personal  interest  in  the  problems 
raised,  has  given  too  much  space  to  what  our  American  delegates 
told  the  English  about  philosophy.  Certainly  he  read  with  more 
than  usual  interest  certain  of  the  other  papers,  notably  the  Sym- 
posium on  "The  Character  of  Cognitive  Acts."  The  most  striking 
proposition  here  is  that  of  Mr.  G.  E.  Moore,  to  the  effect  that  in  all 
cognition,  however  simple,  a  particular,  as  for  instance  a  sense  datum, 
is  subsumed  under  a  universal,  and  that  there  is  no  other  character- 
istic, such  as  the  existence  of  a  knower  or  an  act  of  knowing,  which 
is  thus  uniformly  found.  This  thesis  suggests  that  Mr.  Moore  is 
working  towards  a  new  theory  of  mind,  and  we  await  with  interest 
its  further  development.  The  other  symposium  contributions  offer 
little  that  is  new,  though  they  are  acute  and  hold  the  attention. 

The  reviewer  was  less  impressed  by  Dean  Inge's  Presidential 
Address,  "Is  the  Time  Series  Reversible?"  than  he  usually  is  by 
what  the  Dean  writes  on  philosophy,  though  no  one  could  help 
being  amused  by  the  parting  shot  at  Einstein,  "I  feel  in  my  bones 
that  this  prophet  of  relativity  is  not  likely  to  be  a  true  friend  to 
Platonism."  Mr.  C.  A.  Richardson,  in  "The  New  Materialism," 
expresses  his  distaste  for  most  of  the  New  Realists,  because  they  have 
done  away  with  what  a  certain  sophomore  student  of  philosophy  once 
called  "the  myself  part  of  me."  If  the  present  reviewer  got  little 


418  JOURNAL  OF  PII1LOSOPH  Y 

out  of  Miss  Oakeley 's  paper  on  Professor  Driesch,  this  is  probably  the 
reviewer's  own  fault,  though  it  may  be  partly  attributable  to  Pro- 
fessor Driesch. 

There  remain  two  logical  papers.  That  by  Mr.  F.  C.  S.  Schiller, 
"On  Arguing  in  a  Circle,"  is  one  of  his  chronic  attacks  on  the  Abso- 
lute, but  it  will  probably  awaken  neither  the  Absolute  nor  his  min- 
ions. Mr.  Schiller  has  never  equalled  elsewhere  his  one  really  ad- 
mirable logical  paper,  his  contribution  to  Singer's  Studies  in  the 
History  and  Method  of  Science  (1917).  Miss  Dorothy  Wrinch  con- 
tributes a  somewhat  over-ambitious  paper,  at  least  as  regards  its 
title,  "On  the  Structure  of  Scientific  Inquiry."  It  contains  many 
good  things  in  matters  of  detail.  Especially  interesting  is  her  treat- 
ment of  what  she  calls  "true  analogy,"  or  identity  of  form  of  solu- 
tion in  problems  from  otherwise  different  fields.  One  earlier  passage 
deserves  quotation  in  full.  "The  domain  of  logic  in  science  is  over- 
whelmingly wide  and  correspondingly  difficult.  No  student  who  has 
any  knowledge  of  the  development  of  science  can  deny  this.  And 
yet  the  paramount  importance  of  logic  is  very  seldom  realized  and 
the  study  of  it  is  quite  often  avoided  and  only  infrequently  under- 
taken by  those  who  seek  to  make  contributions  to  our  knowledge  of  the 
world.  Professor  D'Arcy  Thompson  in  the  wonderful  epilogue  to 
Growth  and  Form  (1917)  hints  at  the  aesthetic  glories  of  such  a 
treatment  of  the  world,  in  words  which  are  full  of  hope  and  en- 
couragement, and  should  earn  for  him  the  gratitude  of  all  logicians." 

H.  T.  COSTELI/>. 
TRINITY  COLLEGE,  HABTTORD. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

SCIENTIA.  January,  1922.  Les  sciences  grecques  et  leur 
transmission.  7.  Splendeur  et  decadence  de  la  science  grecque  (pp. 
1-10):  J.  L.  HEIBERG  (Kjobenhavn). -Rapid  historical  sketch  of 
Greek  science.  The  Origin  of  Binary  Stars  (pp.  11-22) :  J.  II. 
JEANS  (Cambridge,  England). -Concludes  that  some  binaries  are  due 
to  fission,  others  to  independent  nuclei  in  an  original  nebula.  Inter- 
esting for  its  exposition  of  the  methods  by  which  these  results  were 
reached.  La  contribution  que  les  divers  pays  ont  donnee  au  dcvelop- 
pement  de  la  biologic  (pp.  23-36) :  MAURICE  CAULLEBY  ( Paris) .- 
Largely  a  comparison  of  German  scientific  work  with  that  of  other 
countries,  claiming  to  find  in  Germany  excellent  organization  of 
research,  but  methods  inclining  towards  a  twisting  of  facts  to  fit 
a  priori  theories.  La  question  sociale  (pp.  37-46) :  VUfredo  Pareto 
(Lausanne)  .-Surveys  the  history  of  the  conflict  of  social  classes  and 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  419 

the  problem  of  property,  a  many  sided  but  rather  confused  summary, 
that  hardly  does  its  author  justice.  La  paix  est-elle  une  paix  anglo- 
saxonne?  (pp.  47-56)  :  EDOUARD  GUYOT  (Rennes).-How  the  differ- 
ence of  interests  has  led  France  and  England  apart  since  the  war — an 
interesting  French  view  of  English  policies.  Les  effets  de  la  guerre 
sur  la  proportion  des  sexes  dans  les  naissances  (pp.  57-62) :  F. 
SAVORGNAN  (Messina)  .-The  author  takes  it  as  proved  that  in  the 
countries  hardest  hit  by  the  war,  the  proportion  of  male  births  in- 
creased. He  attributes  this  to  the  diminution  of  total  births,  with  its 
resultant  better  condition  of  the  mothers,  so  that  fewer  males  were 
still-born.  Reviews  of  Scientific  Books  and  Periodicals. 

Endara,  Julio.  Jose  Ingenieros  y  el  Porvenir  de  la  Filosofia. 
Second  edition.  Buenos  Aires:  Agencia  General  de  Libreria. 
1922.  Pp.  100. 

Rueff,  Jacques.  Des  Sciences  Physiques  aux  Sciences  Morales:  In- 
troduction a  1'etude  de  la  morale  et  de  1'economie  politique  ra- 
tionelles.  Paris :  Felix  Alcan.  1922.  Pp.  xx  -f-  202.  8  fr. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 
RESPONDING  TO  THE  STIMULUS 

To  the  Editors  of  the  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY: 

The  only  reason  I  have  to  offer  for  taking  the  liberty  to  reply 
to  Dr.  Hunter's  letter  to  the  anti-behaviorists  (in  the  issue  of  May 
25),  though  it  is  together  with  a  score  of  others  that  my  name  ap- 
pears on  his  list,  is  to  inform  him  that  there  are  more  than  two 
behaviorists  in  this  world,  as  I  hope  to  show  in  my  forthcoming  little 
book,  Psychology  and  Behaviorism;  and  that  in  his  hunt  for  what 
appears  to  him  an  avis  rara  he  has  allowed  some  of  the  best  repre- 
sentatives of  the  species,  like  E.  B.  Holt,  E.  A.  Singer  and  Max 
Meyer,  perhaps  too  B.  Bode  and  Mrs.  De  Laguna,  either  to  slip  in 
among  the  antis  or  to  elude,  his  aquiline  eye  altogether. 

I  heartily  agree  with  him  in  his  refusal  to  recognize  the  new 
systems  of  behaviorism  that  are  continually  being  put  on  the  market 
as  genuine  products,  but  if  he  asks  us  introspectionists  (and  most  of 
the  anti-behaviorists  he  draws  up  in  his  formidable  list  are  anything 
but  introspectionists)  to  do  a  little  self-analysis,  may  we  not  ask 
him  en  revanche  to  return  the  courtesy  and  explain  objectively  why 
so  many  objectivists  in  psychology  should  give  him  the  impression 
that  they  are  paranoiacs  seeing  "an  enemy  in  everyone  not  an 
anointed  introspectionist"  and  detecting  a  "danger  in  all  objective 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

study"?  And  were  these  "anointed  introspectionists"  really  so 
fearful  of  the  inroads  of  behaviorism,  would  they  be  advocating  new 
systems  of  behaviorism  rather  than  eschewing  the  slightest  associa- 
tion with  the  radical  movement  and  employing  the  term  behaviorism 
only  in  criticism?  Dr.  Hunter  implies  that  every  psychologist  who 
is  not  a  behaviorist  d  la  Watson — I  suppose  in  accordance  with  the 
famous  dictum  "He  who  is  not  for  me  is  against  me" — must  be  an 
anti-behaviorist,  but  since  he  has  found  only  two  behaviorists,  Wat- 
son and  Weiss,  he  himself,  by  implication,  must  be  classed  as  an 
anti — and  now  who  will  hunt  the  hunter? 

Our  interrogator  is  apparently  given  to  paradox,  for  after  ad- 
mitting that  he  has  followed  "your  papers  during  the  last  ten 
years  with  keen  interest  and  much  profit"  he  rather  ungratefully 
asks  "Why  do  you  write  so  much?"  May  I  answer  for  my  part 
that  it  was  this  polygraphy — if  I  may  use  the  word  in  an  archaic 
sense — which  has  enabled  me  to  undertake  the  very  task  which 
Dr.  Hunter  was  anxious  to  have  performed,  and  to  answer  at  con- 
siderable length  his  questions:  "Who  are  the  behaviorists?"  and 
"Have  you  ever  brought  together  a  bibliography  of  this  topic  for 
the  last  decade?" 

A.  A.  ROBACK. 

HABVARD  UNIVERSITY. 

Dr.  Edwin  G.  Boring,  professor  of  experimental  psychology  at 
Clark  University,  has  been  appointed  associate  professor  of  psychol- 
ogy at  Harvard  University.  Dr.  Herbert  S.  Langfeld  has  been 
promoted  from  an  assistant  professorship  to  associate  professorship 
at  Harvard. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  16  AUGUST  3,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE.    II 
THE  EMPIRICAL  BASIS  OP  GEOMETRY 

IT  is  so  long  since  geometry  reached  the  assured  position  of  a  deduc- 
tive science,  that  it  is  hard  for  us  now  to  realize  that  it  was 
ever  in  an  inductive  stage.  But  this,  of  course,  is  plain  historical 
fact.  The  geometry  of  the  Egyptians  was  a  body  of  practical  rules 
of  mensuration,  which  were  the  outcome  of  long  experience  and 
careful  observation — though  they  were  far  from  exact,  according  to 
our  standards.  And  the  geometry  of  the  early  Pythagoreans,  while 
it  exhibits  from  the  outset  the  Greek  interest  in  pure  theory,  and 
was  thus  destined  to  develop  into  the  organization  of  consecutive 
demonstrations  which  the  science  in  its  classical  form  exhibits, 
was  still  essentially  empirical  in  its  methods  and  standards. 

When  one  speaks  in  this  way  of  an  inductive  and  a  deductive  stage 
in  the  development  of  a  science,  it  is  not  suggested  that  in  the  former 
stage  deductive  processes  are  not  employed.  The  distinction  rather 
is  that  when  the  deductive  stage  has  been  reached  induction  is  no 
longer  used  as  a  method  of  proof,  but  only  for  purposes  of  discovery 
or  of  illustration.  When  it  has  been  demonstrated,  for  example,  that 
the  three  internal  angle-bisectors  of  a  triangle  meet  in  a  point,  there 
is  no  necessity  for  confirming  the  result  with  rule  and  compasses; 
and  if,  on  actual  trial,  the  three  bisectors  should  appear  not  to  con- 
verge, one  would  blame  the  draughtsman  or  his  instruments,  not  the 
principles  involved. 

In  the  case  of  geometry,  the  deductive  stage  waited  upon  the  con- 
ception of  the  point — of  that  which  has  position  and  not  magnitude. 
The  existence  of  bodies  must  be  attested,  directly  or  indirectly,  by 
specific  observations.  The  existence  of  points  is  attested  by  general 
axioms,  which  recognize  no  distinction  between  possible  points  and 
actual  points.  Take  away  all  bodies,  and  the  system  of  points  is  con- 
ceived to  remain  the  same.  Thus  the  system  of  points  is  space  as 
such — space  which  may  be  full  or  empty  without  its  characteristic 
properties  being  in  any  way  affected. 

421 


422  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

The  earliest  Greek  geometers  knew  nothing  of  the  point:  and 
accordingly  they  could  not  make  the  distinction  between  space  and 
extended  matter.  The  folk-mind,  as  well  as  early  science,  has  the 
two  conceptions,  "something"  and  "nothing,"  the  former  of  which 
is  often  identified  by  science  with  "matter,"  the  latter  with  "empty 
space."  But  the  latter  identification,  at  least,  is  inexact.  Empty 
space  can  be  conceived  only  as  distinguished  from  filled  space,  not 
as  distinguished  from  matter;  for  space  is  space,  whether  filled  or 
empty.  The  folk-mind  also  has  a  conception  of  "place" — a  place 
where  something  may  or  may  not  be.  And  it  has  the  closely  re- 
lated conception  of  a  "hole"  which  may  be  made  in  a  given  place, 
and  which  again  may  be  filled  up.  These  also  are  not  equivalent  to 
the  notion  of  space,  because  of  the  relativity  to  actual  "somethings" 
which  they  contain.  A  place  in  a  moving  cart  moves  with  the  cart. 
A  hole  in  a  log  disappears  when  the  log  is  burned  up.  If  there  is 
an  unmoved  place,  it  is  at,  in,  or  on  something  that  is  unmoved. 
The  developing  scientific  consciousness  appropriates  these  concep- 
tions, and  interprets  them  in  the  light  of  its  space-conception.  For 
science,  it  is  primarily  the  point  that  has  position ;  and  the  position 
of  a  point  is  primarily  relative  only  to  other  points.  The  hole,  if 
really  unfilled,  becomes  a  "vacuum,"  i.e.,  empty  space;  and,  con- 
trariwise, infinite  space  itself  becomes  the  "universal  receptacle" — 
a  hole,  if  you  please,  that  is  not  a  hole  in  anything.  But  these  are 
developments  that  distinctly  belong  to  science,  not  to  the  folk-con- 
sciousness, and  not  even  to  the  beginnings  of  science. 

The  Pythagoreans  long  confused  mist  and  darkness  with  empty 
space.  And,  at  the  same  time,  they  thought  of  space  (or  mist)  as 
made  up  of  discrete  units.  Two  of  these  units,  side  by  side,  made 
the  shortest  possible  line.  Three  were  necessary  to  make  a  surface. 
A  little  pyramidal  heap  of  four  was  the  minimum  solid. 

What  is  geometry  without  the  point?  And  how  can  such  a  ge- 
ometry give  rise  to  the  conception  of  the  point?  These  are  the 
questions  which  are  now  to  engage  our  attention.  Unfortunately 
we  can  have  but  slight  guidance  from  the  recorded  history  of  the 
science  in  answering  them.  The  fundamental  principles  that  are 
involved  are  such  as  must  have  come  to  universal  recognition  long 
before  the  beginnings  of  geometry  as  a  distinct  body  of  knowledge. 
Accordingly,  they  are  not  regarded  by  primitive  scientists  as  worthy 
of  explicit  statement ;  and  when  geometry  reached  a  stage  in  which 
the  systematic  statement  of  its  foundations  was  felt  to  be  a  desid- 
eratum, the  conception  of  the  point,  with  the  attendant  abstraction 
of  space  from  matter,  was  already  firmly  established,  and  no  need 
was  felt  for  going  behind  it. 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  423 

The  foundations  of  an  inductive  science  differ  necessarily  in  the 
most  radical  fashion  from  the  formal  beginnings  of  a  deductive  sci- 
ence. The  latter  has  its  few  indefinables  and  its  set  of  axioms.  The 
inductive  science  has  indefinables  in  plenty,  not  in  the  sense  of 
concepts  that  do  not  need  definition,  but  in  the  sense  of  concepts 
that  are  too  vague  to  admit  of  definition;  and  it  has  unproved 
principles  in  plenty,  which  are  assumed,  not  because  they  are  self- 
evident,  but  because  they  are  plausible.  As  the  science  advances, 
its  earlier  indefinables  may  be  defined,  or  they  may  disappear  by 
reason  of  radical  inconsistencies  that  have  been  discovered  in  them ; 
and,  at  the  same  time,  the  earlier  "axioms"  may  be  demonstrated, 
or  they  may  be  shown  to  be  unsound.  "As  far  as  the  east  is  from 
the  west, ' '  said  the  psalmist,  little  thinking  that  east  and  west  come 
together.  That  bodies  which  are  not  supported  fall  downwards  is 
an  ancient  maxim,  from  which  even  today  our  imaginations  are  not 
wholly  liberated.  With  the  earliest  physicists  it  sometimes  passed 
unquestioned;  witness,  for  example,  Anaximenes's  theory,  that  the 
reason  the  earth  does  not  fall  is  that  its  shape  is  that  of  a  broad 
leaf,  so  that  it  is  supported  by  the  air. 

Starting  from  such  assumptions,  the  inductive  science  attempts 
to  reach  clearness  in  some  one  direction,  leaving  everything  else  un- 
touched for  the  time  being.  Such  attempts  are  generally  destined 
to  meet  with  very  slight  success;  for  the  assumptions  that  are  still 
blindly  made  vitiate  the  whole  procedure.  But  there  is  no  other  way. 
We  can  not  move  our  whole  thought-world  at  once.  It  is  only  by 
using  the  solid  earth  of  common  sense  as  a  fulcrum  that  we  can  hope 
to  budge  some  one  block  of  prejudice.  It  is  only  by  trusting  to  the 
great  mass  of  our  opinions  as  if  they  were  absolute  knowledge,  that 
we  can  hope  to  correct  some  special  misconception.  Success  comes 
when,  by  good  fortune,  the  unsteadiness  of  our  fulcrum  does  not 
markedly  affect  the  work  performed. 

Let  us  enumerate  some  of  the  common-sense  conceptions  which 
inductive  geometry  must  use  in  order  to  give  clearness  to  its  own 
conceptions.1 

First  in  order  stands  the  physical  solid.  In  some  rough  fashion 
this  conception  must  have  belonged  to  men  since  they  began  to  reflect 
at  all.  Solids  behave  in  characteristically  different  ways  from 
liquids,  as  well  as  from  wind  and  fire.  They  impress  us  differently, 
and  we  manipulate  them  differently — in  just  what  ways  we  need  not 
specify.  Nor  need  we  stumble  over  the  fact  that  there  are  all  degrees 

1  A  first  sketch  of  the  theory  here  developed  is  contained  in  an  article  on 
"The  Nature  of  Primary  Qualities,"  in  the  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  XXII, 
pp.  504-6. 


424  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY 

of  viscosity  and  solidity  that  separate  the  typical  liquid  from  the  typ- 
ical solid ;  much  less  distress  ourselves  with  the  thought  that  not  even 
the  typical  solids  are  absolutely  rigid,  even  when  they  are  not  long 
and  thin  enough  to  be  bent  like  wire.  We  put  all  such  sophistications 
aside ;  and,  without  pretense  of  definition,  we  boldly  assume  that  we 
mean  something  definite  enough  by  a  "solid,"  and  that  solids  in  gen- 
eral  are  good  enough  solids  for  the  immediate  purposes  of  our  science. 

Secondly,  there  is  motion,  with  its  negative  rest.  We  have  a 
variety  of  ways  of  perceiving  motion,  both  in  our  own  bodies  and  in 
other  bodies.  As  little  as  in  the  case  of  the  solid  shall  we  attempt 
to  be  precise  or  to  guard  our  conceptions  from  ambiguity.  We  shall 
not  ask  ourselves  whether  by  "motion"  we  mean  absolute  or  rela- 
tive motion,  or,  if  the  latter,  relative  to  what.  No ;  we  simply  mean 
motion,  as  we  see  it  and  feel  it.  Again,  we  do  not  allow  ourselves 
to  be  perplexed  by  the  image  of  an  Heraclitean  flux;  nor  by  the 
thought  that,  as  observation  becomes  more  exact,  many  things  that 
seemed  to  be  at  rest  are  found  to  be  in  motion,  so  that  it  is  doubtful 
whether  in  the  world  anything  is  at  rest  either  absolutely  or  relatively 
to  anything  else.  We  ignore  all  such  considerations.  By  rest  we 
mean  the  condition  of  most  of  the  things  about  us,  most  of  the  time, 
as  they  appear  to  common  observation. 

Thirdly,  there  is  contact.  This  also  we  have  various  ways  of  per- 
ceiving, not  all  of  which  are  always  possible,  but  which  generally 
confirm  one  another.  We  can  often  see  that  two  solids  are  in  con- 
tact with  each  other,  and  hear  when  they  are  brought  into  contact. 
We  have  a  special  sensation  that  informs  us  when  something  touches 
our  own  body ;  and,  by  a  change  in  its  intensity,  this  sensation  also 
informs  us  when  a  solid  which  we  are  holding  touches  another  solid. 
Strain  sensations  serve  the  same  purpose.  There  is  also  this  familiar 
and  fairly  trustworthy  test:  that  it  is  only  when  two  solids  are  in 
contact  with  each  other  or  are  both  in  contact  with  a  third  (inter- 
vening) solid  that  we  can  cause  a  movement  in  one  of  the  two  by 
moving  the  other. 

Lastly,  there  is  simultaneity,  whether  it  be  of  momentary  events 
or  of  more  or  less  enduring  conditions.  However,  on  account  of  the 
narrowness  of  the  field  of  human  attention,  simultaneity  can,  in 
general,  be  attested  only  by  an  absence  of  relevant  change  as  our 
observation  shifts  to  and  fro  between  the  compared  objects,  and 
hence  can,  in  general,  mean  only  the  temporal  overlapping  of  con- 
ditions. 

How  are  these  conceptions  involved  in  geometrical  observations? 
The  answer  is  not  far  to  seek.  Spatial  measurement  is  an  operation 
performed  primarily  upon  solids.  To  measure  a  liquid  or  a  vapor 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  425 

is,  in  general,  to  measure  its  solid  container.  Moreover,  the  measur- 
ing-rod itself  is  in  all  cases  a  solid,  either  rigid  in  itself,  or — as  in 
the  case  of  a  taut  string — given  a  temporary  rigidity.  Geometry,  as 
the  science  of  spatial  measurement,  is  thus  a  science  of  solids ;  and, 
while  endeavoring  to  refine  its  conception  of  certain  of  the  properties 
of  solids,  it  must  necessarily  take  for  granted  at  the  outset  a  gross 
common-sense  notion  of  the  solid  as  such. 

More  precisely,  the  operation  of  measurement,  in  its  fundamental 
form,  involves  the  observation  of  the  occurrence  or  non-occurrence 
of  the  simultaneous  contact  of  one  solid  with  two  others,  which  may, 
indeed,  be  parts  of  a  single  solid.  There  are,  of  course,  other  modes 
of  measurement :  directly  by  the  eye  or  hand ;  indirectly  by  the  time 
which  a  familiar  movement,  such  as  walking,  over  the  given  distance 
requires.  Or  a  measuring-rod  can  be  used  without  actual  contact. 
But,  when  we  observe  that  one  solid  touches  two  others  simulta- 
neously, we  know,  with  an  assurance  limited  only  by  our  confidence  in 
that  observation,  that  the  distance  between  the  two  is  not  greater 
than  the  length  of  the  intervening  one.  And  when  we  find  that,  try 
as  we  may,  we  can  not  make  one  solid  touch  two  others  at  once,  we 
are  assured  that  the  distance  between  these  two  is  greater  than  the 
length  of  the  one.  For  the  purposes  of  empirical  geometry,  that  is 
the  meaning  of  these  observations. 

In  all  this  it  is  assumed  that  our  powers  of  manipulating  the  solid 
with  which  we  try  to  touch  two  others  are  practically  unlimited; 
and,  in  particular,  that  we  can  freely  move  any  fourth  body  that 
might  otherwise  interfere  with  the  process.2  As  a  matter  of  fact  our 
ability  freely  to  manipulate  objects,  or  to  move  them  so  that  they  will 
not  interfere  with  our  manipulation  of  other  objects — or,  for  that 
matter,  to  keep  them  at  rest  while  other  objects  about  them  are  mov- 
ing— is  decidedly  limited.  "We  must,  of  course,  base  our  inductions 
on  the  observations  where  the  required  conditions  are  satisfied ;  and 
we  then  assume  that  were  our  powers  greater  we  should  have  been 
able  to  make  similar  observations  in  the  other  cases.  In  this  respect 
empirical  geometry  does  not  differ  from  other  empirical  sciences. 

Just  as  men  may  be  assumed  to  possess,  from  the  earliest  stages 
of  reflection,  some  notion  of  the  solid,  of  rest  and  motion,  of  contact, 
and  of  simultaneity,  so  they  may  equally  be  assumed  to  possess  some 
notion  of  distance  and  of  length.  We  can  not,  however,  in  what  fol- 
lows make  any  express  appeal  to  this  phase  of  early  thought ;  for  it 
is  precisely  here  that  our  endeavor  to  substitute  clear  definition  for 
common  sense  must  begin. 

2  Here,  in  addition  to  the  conceptions  enumerated  above,  a  vague  concep- 
tion of  force  is  involved. 


426  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

The  first  step  is  to  bring  before  our  attention  a  certain  funda- 
mental induction,  which  may  be  called  the  principle  of  measurement, 
and  upon  which  our  whole  further  procedure  rests : 

If  the  solids  A,  B,  C,  and  D  are  at  rest,  and  if  there  is  at  least 
one  solid  2T  which  can  be  brought  into  simultaneous  contact  with  A 
and  B,  but  can  not  in  any  way  be  brought  into  simultaneous  contact 
with  C  and  D,  then  there  is  no  solid  that  can  connect  *  C  and  D  but 
can  not  connect  A  and  B. 

Attention  must  be  called  to  the  condition  that  no  one  of  the  four 
solids,  A,  B,  C,  and  D,  shall  move.  If  any  one  of  them  is  observed 
to  move,  further  observation  often  shows  that  it  is  then  possible  to 
find  a  solid  that  can  connect  C  and  D  but  not  A  and  B,  But,  further- 
more, sometimes  it  happens,  even  when  no  one  of  the  four  has  been 
observed  to  move,  that  nevertheless  the  principle  fails  to  hold.  In 
that  case,  we  say,  perhaps,  that  one  of  the  objects  actually  moved, 
though  we  did  not  observe  it,  either  because  we  were  not  watching  it 
at  the  time,  or — and  this  is  the  important  point — because  our  obser- 
vation was  defective.  We  are  often  ready,  in  such  a  case,  to  condemn 
an  observation  as  defective,  even  though  we  have  no  reason  to  be- 
lieve that  it  was  less  careful  than  any  observations  upon  which  we  im- 
pose complete  reliance.  Or  we  say  that  in  the  interval  between  the 
tests  some  change  occurred  in  the  capacity  of  one  of  the  manipulated 
solids  to  connect  other  solids. 

Thus  this  fundamental  induction  of  geometry  is  not  supported  by 
evidence  that  is  in  itself  perfectly  consistent.  Direct  observation 
does  not  prove  it  to  be  invariably  true,  but  rather  goes  to  show  that 
it  is  sometimes,  though  comparatively  rarely,  contrary  to  fact.  We 
follow  in  the  induction  the  overwhelmingly  great  mass  of  our  obser- 
vations; and  we  simplify  our  experience  by  bringing  the  apparent 
exceptions  into  line.  The  simplification  is  the  greater,  in  that  we 
are  thus  enabled  to  extend  our  induction  to  all  solids  whatsoever, 
whether  they  be  at  rest  or  not.  It  now  becomes : 

If  A,  B,  C,  D,  and  X  be  any  solids,  and  if,  at  any  moment,  X  can 
connect  A  and  B  but  can  not  connect  C  and  D,  then,  at  that  moment, 
no  T  exists  which  can  connect  C  and  D  but  not  A  and  B. 

The  proposition  at  which  we  thus  arrive  may  be  brought  under 
a  wider  induction  that  is  reached  as  follows : 

In  the  first  place,  if  there  exist  two  solids,  X  and  T,  such  that 
while  X  touches  A,  and  Y  touches  B,  they  can  at  the  same  time  be 
made  to  touch  each  other ;  and  if  X  and  Y  can  not  be  made  in  this 
sense  to  "connect"  C  and  D;  then  no  solid,  and  no  pair  of  solids, 
can  be  found  that  can  connect  C  and  D  but  not  A  and  B. 

•We  shall  hereafter  use  this  term  instead  of  the  cumbersome  phrase,  "be 
in  simultaneous  contact  with." 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  427 

At  the  same  time,  let  us  note  that  if  X  and  T  can  connect  A  and 
B  in  the  order,  "A  touches  X,  which  touches  Y,  which  touches  B," 
X  and  Y  can  also  be  made  to  connect  A  and  B  in  the  order,  "A 
touches  Y,  which  touches  X,  which  touches  B." 

In  the  second  place,  if  there  exist  one  or  more  solids,  V,  W,  X, 
Y  .  .  .  •  which  can  be  made  to  connect  A  and  B  in  that  order,  then 
they  can  be  made  to  connect  A  and  B  in  any  order  whatsoever. 
And  if,  further,  they  can  not  be  made  to  connect  the  solids 
C  and  D,  then  no  solid  or  chain  of  solids  *  can  be  found  which  can 
connect  C  and  D  but  not  A  and  B. 

In  the  third  place,  where  there  are  more  than  two  solids  inserted 
between  A  and  B,  it  is  not  necessary  in  our  tests  that  all  the  con- 
tacts be  simultaneous.  For  example,  let  V  touch  A  and  W;  then, 
if  W  remains  at  rest,  V  may  be  removed ;  when  X  has  been  brought 
into  contact  with  W,  W  may  be  removed;  and  so  on,  until  contact 
with  B  is  secured.  However,  when  it  comes  to  proving  that  a  con- 
nection between  A  and  B  can  not  be  effected  by  a  given  combination 
of  solids,  this  method  is  cumbersome;  for  the  removed  solids  must  be 
again  and  again  replaced,  in  order  to  test  whether  some  new  mode  of 
contact  may  not  make  it  possible  for  the  connection  to  be  secured. 

In  the  fourth  place,  a  solid  that  has  been  removed  according  to 
the  method  above  described  may  be  used  again,  either  at  once  or  later, 
so  that  one  or  more  solids  may  be  used  any  number  of  times.  If, 
in  connecting  A  and  B,  V  has  been  used  ra  times,  W  n  times,  X  p 
times,  etc.,  then,  no  matter  how  the  order  is  changed,  it  is  always 
possible  to  connect  A  and  B  by  using  the  intervening  solids  the 
same  numbers  of  times.  And  if  C  and  D  can  not  be  connected  in 
this  way,  then  there  is  no  proportion  in  which  any  collection  of  solids 
can  be  used  to  connect  C  and  D,  in  which  they  can  not  also  be  made 
to  connect  A  and  B. 

In  particular,  any  two  solids  may  be  used  alternately,  as  often 
as  desired,  in  effecting  a  connection. 

We  may  repeat  here,  with  reference  to  the  formation  of  chains 
of  solids,  and  their  manipulation,  a  remark  that  was  made  above  with 
reference  to  the  manipulation  of  solids  as  such.  The  number  of 
"links"  which  we  can  manage  varies  greatly  both  with  the  links  that 
are  employed  and  the  conditions  under  which  we  employ  them.  The 
inductions  of  geometry  are  based  upon  observations  made  under 
conditions  where  we  are  able  to  use  any  and  all  links  that  we  wish 
to  use,  as  often  as  we  please ;  that  is  to  say,  where,  for  the  purposes 
of  the  observation,  no  limitations  are  felt.  Accordingly,  we  assume 

*  This  brief  and  convenient  expression  will  be  employed  frequently. 


I'JS 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


that  any  solids  whatsoever  may  be  combined  in  a  chain,  each  of  them 
being  reinserted  as  often  as  we  please.  Here  again  geometry  does 
not  differ  from  other  empirical  sciences. 

We  are  now  prepared  for  the  following  definitions: 


I*  If  A,  B,  C,  and  D  are 
such  that  a  solid  (or  chain  of 
solids)  X  can  be  found,  which 
can  connect  A  and  B  but  not 
C  and  D;  then  C  and  D  are  said 
to  be  farther  apart  than  A  and 
B. 


P  If  the  solid  (or  chain  of 
solids)  M  and  the  solid  (or  chain 
of  solids)  N  are  such  that  two 
solids,  X  and  T,  can  be  found, 
which  M  can  connect,  while  N 
can  not;  then  M  is  said  to  be 
longer  than  N. 

Thus  we  have  brought  before  us  the  "indefinable"  relation  as- 
sumed by  metrical  geometry  in  its  deductive  form — not,  however,  as 
subsisting  between  pairs  of  points  (of  which,  as  yet,  we  know  noth- 
ing), but  as  subsisting  between  pairs  of  solids.  At  the  same  time, 
there  is  introduced  the  relation  "to  be  longer  than,"  which  we  had 
no  occasion  to  note  in  the  earlier  discussion,  but  which  stands  in  a 
curious  correspondence  with  the  relation  "to  be  farther  apart  than." 
This  correspondence  we  shall  continue  to  indicate  by  means  of  par- 
allel columns. 

From  the  fundamental  induction  we  may  at  once  conclude : 


If  A  and  B  are  farther  apart 
than  C  and  D,  C  and  D  are  not 
farther  apart  than  A  and  B. 

If  A  and  B  are  farther  apart 
than  C  and  D,  and  C  and  D  are 
farther  apart  than  E  and  F; 
then  A  and  B  are  farther  apart 
than  E  and  F. 

II*  If  A  and  B  are  not 
farther  apart  than  C  and  D,  and 
C  and  D  are  not  farther  apart 
than  A  and  B;  then  A  and  B 
are  said  to  be  just  as  far  apart 
as  C  and  D. 

Ill0  The  distance  between  A 
and  B  is  the  class  of  pairs  of 
solids  that  are  just  as  far  apart 
as  A  and  B  (or  the  property  of 
being  just  as  far  apart  as  A  and 
B). 


If  M  is  longer  than  N,  N  is 
not  longer  than  M. 

If  M  is  longer  than  N,  and  N 
is  longer  than  P;  then  M  is 
longer  than  P. 


IP  If  M  is  not  longer  than 
N,  and  N  is  not  longer  than  M ; 
then  M  is  said  to  be  just  as  long 
as  N. 


Ill6  The  length  of  M  is  the 
class  of  solids  (or  chains  of 
solids)  that  are  just  as  long  as 
M  (or  the  property  of  being  just 
as  long  as  M). 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  429 

The  double  form  of  these  last  two  definitions  has  been  sufficiently 
explained  in  another  connection.8 

IVa    If  A  and  B  are  farther  IV&    If  M  is  longer  than  N, 

apart  than  C  and  D,  the  distance       the  length  of  M  is  said  to  be 
between  A  and  B  is  said  to  be       greater  than  the  length  of  N. 
greater   than  the   distance   be- 
tween C  and  D. 

It  is  easily  proved  that  the  relation  ' '  greater-than, ' '  as  thus  sub- 
sisting between  distances  on  the  one  hand,  and  between  lengths  on 
the  other,  is  asymmetrical  and  transitive. 

"We  must  now  pass  on  to  consider  the  relations  that  may  subsist 
between  a  distance  and  a  length : 

V°    If  M  can  connect  A  and  V6    If  M  can  connect  A  and 

B,  but  can  not  connect  any  pair  B,  but  no  solid  (or  chain  of 
of  solids  that  are  farther  apart  solids)  N,  such  that  M  is  longer 
than  A  and  B;  then  the  distance  than  N,  can  connect  A  and  B; 
between  A  and  B  is  said  to  be  then  the  length  of  M  is  said  to 
equal  to  the  length  of  M,  be  equal  to  the  distance  between 

A  and  B. 

It  will  be  recalled,  that,  treating  distances  and  lengths  as  classes, 
we  do  not  speak  of  one  distance's  being  equal  to  another  distance, 
nor  of  one  length's  being  equal  to  another  length,  but  of  identical 
lengths  and  identical  distances.  But  a  distance  and  a  length  can 
not  be  identical ;  hence  the  necessity  of  the  above  definitions. 

The  two  following  propositions  are  easily  established : 
If  the  distance  between  A  and  If  the  length  of  M  is  equal  to 

B  is  equal  to  the  length  of  M,  the  distance  between  A  and  B, 
the  length  of  M  is  equal  to  the  the  distance  between  A  and  B 
distance  between  A  and  B.  is  equal  to  the  length  of  M. 

VIa    If  the  distance  between  VP    If  the  length  of  M  is 

A  and  B  is  greater  than  a  dis-  greater  than  a  length  that  is 
tance  that  is  equal  to  the  length  equal  to  the  distance  between  A 
of  M ,  it  is  said  to  be  greater  than  and  B,  it  is  said  to  be  greater 
the  length  of  M .  than  the  distance  between  A  and 

B. 

It  will  be  observed  that  up  to  this  point  our  account  of  distances 
and  of  lengths  has  been  perfectly  symmetrical.  At  this  point  the 
symmetry  breaks  down. 

VIP    The  sum  of  the  lengths 
of  M  and  N  is  the  length  of  the 
chain  consisting  of  M  and  N. 
5  See  the  remarks  on  Definition  II  in  the  preceding  article. 


430  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

This  definition  can  not  be  duplicated  for  distances,  for  the  simple 
reason  that  while  there  are  chains  of  solids,  there  are  no  analogous 
chains  of  pairs  of  solids;  or,  as  we  may  express  the  matter,  while 
there  are  chains  of  lengths,  we  are  acquainted  with  no  chains  of 
distances.  Hence  the  sum  of  two  distances  must  be  defined  in- 
directly, in  terms  of  the  sum  of  the  corresponding  lengths: 

VIIa  The  sum  of  the  dis- 
tances between  A  and  B  and 
between  C  and  D  is  the  distance 
that  is  equal  to  the  sum  of  the 
lengths  that  are  equal  respec- 
tively to  the  distance  between  A 
and  B  and  the  distance  between 
C  and  Z>. 

The  importance  of  this  defect  in  the  general  symmetry  will  be 
discussed  below. 

The  effect  of  Definitions  V°  and  V6,  and  of  the  two  propositions 
which  follow  them,  is  to  establish  a  correlation  between  lengths  and 
distances.  The  question  arises  whether  there  can  be  assumed  to 
exist  a  distance  equal  to  every  length,  and  a  length  equal  to  every 
distance. 

On  account  of  the  freedom  with  which  many  solids  can  be  moved, 
it  is  in  general  possible  to  exhibit  a  pair  of  solids  that  are  at  a 
distance  equal  to  the  length  of  a  given  solid  (or  chain  of  solids). 
And,  though  this  can  not  always  be  done,  no  reason  in  any  instance 
appears  to  indicate  that  a  pair  of  solids  at  the  required  distance 
from  each  other  may  not  occur.  Accordingly,  we  assume  that  there 
is  a  distance  equal  to  every  length. 

The  answer  to  the  second  part  of  the  question  involves  the  con- 
sideration of  the  peculiar  sense  in  which  one  solid  may  be  part  of 
another  solid. 

It  often  happens  that  two  solids  can  be  brought  into  contact  with 
each  other  in  such  a  fashion  that  thereafter  they  can  be  manipulated, 
and  may  therefore  be  regarded,  as  a  single  solid.  In  such  a  case, 
the  collection  of  two  solids  is  no  mere  logical  collection,  or  class. 
It  is  a  collection,  between  the  members  of  which  a  relation  subsists 
which  makes  it  a  "unity,"  or  "complex";  and  this  unity,  or  com- 
plex, is  a  solid.  The  two  members  of  the  collection  are  then  called 
parts  of  the  collection  considered  as  a  solid ;  and  the  latter  is  called 
the  whole. 

The  like  may  happen  with  any  number  of  solids. 

It  also  happens  that  a  solid  may  be,  as  we  say,  broken,  that 
is,  undergo  the  reverse  process:  being  changed  into  a  collection  of 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  431 

solids  that  is  not  itself  a  single  solid.  When  this  appears  possible, 
we  may,  independently  of  any  such  actual  process,  regard  the  solid 
as  a  complex  of  those  solids  into  which  it  might  be  broken ;  and  these 
are  then  called  its  parts. 

We  assume  that  if  a  part  of  a  solid  is  in  contact  with  another 
solid,  the  whole  is  also  in  contact  with  that  solid.  This  appears  to  be 
implied  in  the  notion  of  contact,  which  (it  will  be  recalled)  we  have 
not  here  attempted  to  analyze. 

Observation  shows  that  a  whole  is  often  longer  than  one  of  its 
parts,  though  the  part  may  be  just  as  long  as  the  whole.  But  a 
part  can  not  be  longer  than  the  whole.  It  is  generally  possible  to 
break  up  a  solid  into  parts  (and  it  is  thus  legitimate  to  consider  it  as 
already  made  up  of  parts)  such  that  the  whole  is  longer  than  any  one 
of  them;  and  this  process  may,  in  general,  be  continued  until  the 
parts  are  such  that  an  assigned  solid  is  longer  than  any  one  of  them. 
Similarly,  if  a  pair  of  solids  are  not  in  contact  with  each  other,  it 
is  generally  possible  to  break  a  third  solid  into  parts,  no  one  of 
which  can  connect  the  pair.  Furthermore,  though  it  often  happens 
that,  with  the  available  means  of  manipulation,  a  solid  is  unbreak- 
able, it  also  often  becomes  possible  to  break  such  a  solid;  and  no 
absolute  limit  to  the  process  of  continuous  breaking  is  known.  Ac- 
cordingly, we  assume:  (1)  that  if  M  and  N  be  each  any  solid,  M 
may  be  considered  as  made  up  of  parts  such  that  N  is  longer  than 
any  one  of  them;  and,  similarly,  (2)  that  if  M  be  any  solid,  and  if 
A  and  B  be  any  pair  of  solids  that  are  not  in  contact  with  each, 
other,  M  may  be  considered  as  made  up  of  parts  no  one  of  which 
can  connect  A  and  B. 

Observation  further  shows  that  if  a  solid  M  is  longer  than  a 
solid  N,  it  is  in  general  possible  to  divide  M  into  two  parts,  one  of 
which  is  just  as  long  as  N;  and  that  if  the  length  of  M  is  greater 
than  the  distance  between  two  solids,  A  and  B,  which  are  not  in 
contact  with  each  other,  it  is  in  general  possible  to  divide  M  into  two 
parts,  the  length  of  one  of  which  is  equal  to  the  distance  between 
A  and  B.  And,  again,  though  it  often  happens  that  with  the  avail- 
able means  of  manipulation  such  a  division  of  M.  can  not  be  effected, 
some  addition  to  these  means  often  makes  the  operation  possible; 
and  we  see  no  final  limit  to  such  possibilities.  We  therefore  as- 
sume that  if  M  be  longer  than  N,  it  contains  a  part  that  is  just  as 
long  as  N;  and  that  if  its  length  is  greater  than  the  distance  be- 
tween A  and  B  (which  are  not  in  contact  with  each  other),  it  con- 
tains a  part  which  is  equal  to  that  distance. 

A  similar  observation  applies  to  combinations  of  solids.  If  the 
length  of  a  given  chain  is  greater  than  a  given  distance,  it  is,  in 


432  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

general,  possible,  by  omitting  one  or  more  members  of  the  chain,  or 
by  including  only  a  part  of  one  member,  or  both,  to  find  a  length 
equal  to  the  given  distance;  and  we  accordingly  assume  that  this 
is  always  possible. 

Finally,  if  A  and  B  be  any  pair  of  solids,  and  if  V,  W,  X,  etc., 
be  any  collection  of  two  or  more  solids,  it  is,  in  general,  possible  to 
form  a  chain  of  these  latter  solids  (repeating  them  as  often  as  may 
be  desired)  that  can  connect  A  and  J5.  And  though  we  are  not 
always  able  actually  to  effect  the  connection — because  of  the  inac- 
cessibility of  one  or  both  of  the  pair  of  solids,  or  because  of  the  dif- 
ficulty of  manipulating  any  of  the  members  of  the  collection — we 
assume  that  there  is  no  essential  impossibility  in  the  matter,  that  is 
to  say,  none  that  is  not  relative  to  our  limited  powers;  and,  accord- 
ingly, we  hold  that  from  any  collection  of  two  or  more  solids  a 
chain  can  be  formed  that  will  connect  any  given  pair  of  solids." 

It  appears  from  the  foregoing,  that  for  every  length  there  is 
an  equal  distance,  and — if  we  leave  out  of  consideration  pairs  of 
solids  that  are  in  contact  with  each  other — for  every  distance  there 
is  an  equal  length.  It  remains  to  consider  the  one  case  of  which 
exception  has  been  made.  Is  there  a  length  corresponding  to  the 
distance  between  two  solids  that  are  in  contact  with  each  other? 

Our  experience  is  (1)  that  any  solid  will  connect  a  pair  of  solids 
that  are  in  contact,  and  further  (2)  that  there  is  no  solid  that  will 
not  suffice  to  connect  some  pairs  of  solids  that  are  not  in  contact. 
But  this  is  as  much  as  to  say  that,  in  our  experience,  there  is  no 
solid  whose  length  is  equal  to  the  distance  between  two  solids  that 
are  in  contact. 

Nothing,  however,  prevents  us  from  assuming  that,  beyond  the 
limits  of  our  experience,  such  solids  exist.  It  might  be  supposed 
'that  an  assumption  of  this  character  would  be  perfectly  idle  and 
frivolous;  but  that  is  not  necessarily  the  case.  There  are  two  com- 
mon classes  of  motives  that  lead  to  such  assumptions.  What  can 
not  possibly  be  perceived  may  be  assumed  to  exist,  first,  in  order 
to  account  by  its  behavior  for  the  behavior  of  various  things  which 
we  can  perceive;  or,  secondly,  in  order  to  simplify  our  mode  of 
statement  of  many  generalizations  regarding  things  which  we  can 
perceive.  It  is,  indeed,  not  always  clear  which  of  these  two  classes 
a  given  assumption  illustrates.  The  chemical  atom  has  sometimes 
been  regarded  as  a  causal  agent,  sometimes  as  a  fiction  of  merely 
notational  significance. 

8  If  the  collection  consists  of  two  solids,  and  if  these  are  of  the  same 
length,  this  principle  reduces  to  the  so-called  "principle  of  Archimedes,"  that 
the  ratio  between  any  two  distances  is  finite. 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  433 

Let  us  postpone  the  question  of  motive — except  as  the  attractive- 
ness of  an  obvious  symmetry  may  suggest  itself — and  arbitrarily 
assume  that  solids  whose  length  is  equal  to  the  distance  between 
solids  that  are  in  contact  with  each  other  exist ;  and,  in  particular, 
that  whenever  two  other  solids  are  in  contact  with  each  other,  at 
least  one  of  these  supposititious  solids  is  in  contact  with  both.  We 
have  then  arrived  at  the  conception  of  the  point,  as  it  enters  into 
metrical  geometry. 

As  so  conceived,  the  point  has  several  noteworthy  properties. 

1.  Since  it  can  connect  no  solids  that  are  not  already  in  con- 
tact with  each  other,  the  point  does  not  increase  the  length  of  a 
chain  to  which  it  is  added.    In  other  words  the  length  of  the  point 
is  zero. 

2.  The  point  can  contain  no  parts  which  are  not  themselves 
points  in  contact  with  each  other.    For  no  part  can  be  longer  than 
the  whole.    Furthermore,  every  part  must  be  in  contact  with  every 
solid  with  which  any  part  is  in  contact.     Thus  no  part  of  a  point 
can  be  distinguished  in  any  way  from  any  other  part  or  from  the 
whole.    We  therefore  assume  that  the  point  has  no  parts. 

3.  Similarly,  two  points  that  are  in  contact  with  each  other — 
coincident  points — can  have  no  different  properties,  unless  because 
of  some  difference  in  movement.     If  we  assume  that  points,  like 
other  solids,  can  move,  we  need  the  conception  of  coincident  points; 
otherwise  not. 

4.  Since  points  are  not  given  in  experience,  we  can  not  dis- 
tinguish between  an  actual  and  a  possible  point.    If  we  assume  that 
points  exist,  every  possible  point  must  be  regarded  as  actual. 

5.  Accordingly,  if  we  assume  that  points  exist,  we  must  assume 
at  least  one  for  every  possible  contact  between  solids.    In  particular, 
every  two  adjacent  parts  of  any  solid  call  for  at  least  one  point; 
and,  as  the  solid  is  divisible  into  parts  ad  infinitum,  every  solid 
must,  in  this  sense,  "contain"  an  infinite  number  of  points. 

The  points  that  are  thus  requisite  are  indicated  by  the  exist- 
ence-axioms of  geometry. 

6.  Points  group  themselves  in  what  are  called  "surfaces"  and 
"lines"  (or,  as  the  mathematicians  call  them,  "curves").    A  col- 
lection of  points  at  which  two  solids  may  be  in  contact  with  each 
other  is  called  a  "surface."    A  surface  is  thus,  as  we  say,  the  "out- 
side" (or  a  part  of  the  outside)  of  a  possible  solid.    A  collection 
of  points  at  which  three  solids  may  be  in  contact  is  called  a  "line," 
or  "curve."    A  surface,  in  this  sense,  may  consist  of  a  single  line, 
or  even  of  a  single  point ;  and  a  line  may  consist  of  a  single  point. 

But  why  should  we  assume  that  points  exist?     What  reason 


434  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

have  we  for  entertaining  a  supposition,  outrunning,  as  it  does,  the 
limits  of  our  experience? 

In  a  great  many  of  the  measurements  in  which  we  are  interested, 
the  distances  directly  involved  arc  much  greater  than  the  lengths. 
This  is  necessarily  the  case,  for  the  reason  that  so  many  important 
solids  are  too  big  for  us  to  move  them  at  all,  or,  at  any  rate,  to 
move  them  freely.  In  such  a  case  we  measure  the  distance  between 
two  parts  of  the  solid,  or  the  distance  between  two  other  solids 
which  the  solid  in  question  touches.  For  we  can  measure  great  dis- 
tances with  comparative  ease  by  means  of  chains  of  solids,  the 
separate  lengths  of  which  are  of  convenient  magnitude. 

The  distances  with  which  we  have  to  deal  are  often  so  much 
greater  than  the  lengths  of  the  objects  between  which  they  are 
measured,  that  the  lengths  are  altogether  negligible  in  comparison. 
Thus  we  may  measure  the  distance  between  two  little  stakes  at  op- 
posite sides  of  a  valley. 

Where  the  lengths  of  the  solids  are  altogether  negligible,  a  con- 
siderable simplification  of  some  of  the  relations  involved  may  oc- 
cur. The  following  case  is  typical : 

When  a  chain  of  three  solids,  X, 
C,  and  Y,  connects  a  pair  of  solids, 
A  and  B,  we  know  that  the  distance 
between  these  latter  solids  is  not 
greater  than  the  length  of  the  chain. 
Moreover,  the  distance  between  A 
and  C  is  not  greater  than  the  length 
of  X;  and  the  distance  between  C 
and  B  is  not  greater  than  the  length 
of  Y.  It  follows  that  the  distance  between  A  and  B  is  not  greater 
than  the  sum  of  (1)  the  distance  between  A  and  C,  (2)  the  length 
of  C,  and  (3)  the  distance  between  C  and  B.  Now,  if  the  length 
of  C  is  negligible,  we  may  simplify  this  statement,  saying  that  the 
distance  between  A  and  B  is  not  greater  than  the  sum  of  the  dis- 
tance between  A  and  C  and  the  distance  between  C  and  B.  This 
need  not  be  true,  but  it  will  not,  at  any  rate,  be  seriously  false. 

If,  now,  we  suppose  C  to  be  a  point,  the  simplified  statement  be- 
comes universally  and  absolutely  true.  And  if  A  and  B  are  like- 
wise points,  we  may  say  that  the  distance  between  any  two  of  the 
three  points  is  not  greater  than  the  sum  of  their  distances  from  the 
third  point. 

It  may  be  recalled  that  in  a  previous  article  we  used  this  rela- 
tion as  the  basis  of  a  definition  of  the  sum  of  two  distances.  But 
without  points  the  direct  addition  of  distances  is  impossible:  the 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  435 

sum  of  two  distances  is  merely  the  distance  equal  to  the  sum  of  the 
two  lengths  that  are  severally  equal  to  the  given  distances.  With- 
out points  we  can  not  have  a  chain  of  distances,  as  we  have  chains 
of  lengths.7 

With  points  we  can  have  precisely  that:  the  distances  between 
successive  members  of  a  series  of  points. 

But  what  is  there  of  real  value  in  this  simplification  ?  Is  it  not 
over-simplification?  Since,  so  far  as  we  know,  there  are  no  points, 
what  sense  is  there  in  laying  down  propositions  that  are  true  only 
of  points? 

In  answer  we  may  refer  to  the  fact  already  mentioned,  that, 
though  there  are  no  points  in  our  experience,  it  frequently  happens 
that  the  solids  with  which  we  have  to  deal  are  relatively  so  small 
that  their  length  does  not  matter  to  us.  The  condition,  ' '  Let  A,  B, 
and  C  be  three  points,"  is,  to  be  sure,  a  condition  which  we  have 
never  found  realized.  But  we  find  what,  to  us,  are  very  close  ap- 
proaches to  it;  and,  the  nearer  the  approach,  the  smaller  the  mar- 
gin of  possible  error  in  the  conclusion,  "AB  is  not  greater  than  the 
sum  oi  AC  and  CB."  The  geometrical  formula  is  descriptive,  not 
of  any  object  of  our  actual  experience,  but  of  cm  ideally  simplified 
object,  which  the  real  objects  may  approach  indefinitely. 

It  is  interesting  to  recall  that  Galileo  has  made  a  similar  ob- 
servation with  regard  to  the  principles  of  mechanics.  Consider, 
for  example,  the  ''law  of  falling  bodies":  that  they  fall  with  a 
velocity  proportional  to  the  time  that  they  have  been  falling.  Is 
this  law  obeyed  by  the  bodies  that  we  perceive?  Evidently  not  by 
the  falling  leaf  or  feather.  But  many  other  bodies  obey  it  very 
closely — some  so  closely  that  it  is  difficult  or  impossible  to  discover 
any  departure  from  exactness.  But  that  does  not  in  itself  excuse 
the  obvious  exceptions.  The  excuse  for  the  exceptions  is  that  they 
do  not  conform  to  the  essential  conditions  of  the  law.  Their  fall  is 
interfered  with  by  the  resistance  of  the  air;  and  the  law  requires 
that  it  shall  take  place  in  a  vacuum,  where  no  such  interference  is 
possible.  But  in  the  more  favorable  instances  does  the  object  fall 
in  a  vacuum?  No.  We  have  no  means  of  obtaining  a  perfect 
vacuum.  Of  what  value,  then,  is  the  law,  since  it  calls  for  a  condi- 
tion that  is  never  in  our  experience  verified? 

The  answer  is  that,  although  we  can  not  wholly  eliminate  the 
resistance  of  the  medium  through  which  the  body  falls,  we  can  re- 
duce this  resistance  in  various  ways.  Some  bodies  are  of  such 
density  and  of  such  a  shape,  that  they  encounter  a  very  slight  re- 
sistance; and  approximate  vacuums  can  be  formed  in  which  even 

7  Cf.  p.  428. 


436  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

a  feather  falls  like  a  shot.  And  the  more  nearly  the  required  con- 
dition is  satisfied,  the  more  nearly  the  law  is  found  to  be  obeyed — 
the  smaller  is  the  margin  of  error  within  which  a  prediction  ac- 
cording to  the  law  can  be  safely  made.  While,  therefore,  the  law 
is  not  exactly  descriptive  of  any  observable  event,  it  does  describe 
an  ideally  simple  event  which  the  observed  events  approach  at  a 
limit.  As  Galileo  pointed  out,  this  is  the  general  character  of  me- 
chanical laws. 

The  closely  analogous  case  of  the  law  of  the  pendulum — that  the 
period  of  oscillation  is  independent  of  the  amplitude,  and  varies  as 
the  square  of  the  length  of  the  pendulum — is  worth  noticing.  Ap- 
ply this  law  to  the  swinging  chandeliers,  and  it  is  verified,  but  only 
approximately.  As  before,  we  have  to  observe  that  the  conditions 
laid  down  by  the  law  are  not  adequately  met.  The  chandelier  is 
not  a  pendulum.  The  pendulum,  for  instance,  swings  from  a  point, 
or  from  a  straight  line  perpendicular  to  the  plane  of  oscillation; 
the  chandelier  does  not  hang  from  a  point  or  even  from  a  straight 
line.  But  where  is  such  a  pendulum  to  be  found?  It  is  not  to  be 
found.  The  pendulum,  as  mechanics  defines  it,  and  as  the  law  of 
the  pendulum  describes  it,  is  a  thing  lying  altogether  beyond  any 
possible  experience  of  ours — an  ideal,  for  which  we  can  find  ap- 
proximations of  varying  closeness,  but  no  exact  realization. 

This,  as  we  have  seen,  is  likewise  the  nature  of  the  point,  and 
of  the  system  of  points  which  we  call  "space."  A  surveyor's  stake 
is  not  a  point,  nor  is  the  tiny  pencil-dot  which  he  makes  upon  his 
map.  But  the  surveyor  treats  them  as  points,  and  thereby  commits 
no  serious  error.  For  the  purposes  of  his  work  they  are  pretty 
good  points,  as  the  chandelier  is  a  pretty  good  pendulum.  The 
points  in  space  are  the  perfect  type — the  Platonic  archetype,  if  you 
choose — which  the  stakes  and  pencil-dots  resemble,  approximate, 
imitate,  in  whose  characteristic  properties  they  participate,  and  of 
which  they  are,  therefore,  serviceable  illustrations.  When,  in  the 
study  of  material  "points,"  the  laws  of  geometry  are  exactly  veri- 
fied, that  means  that  the  approximation  is  close  enough  to  conceal 
the  error.  But  if  the  verification  is  not  exact,  the  laws  of  geometry 
remain  unrepealed.  The  inexactness  is  attributed  to  the  imperfec- 
tion of  the  conditions.  The  geometry  of  stakes  and  pencil-dots  is 
the  geometry  of  points  plus  an  uncertain  amount  of  unimportant 
variation  from  the  norm. 

Let  us  now  turn  our  attention  to  the  principle  of  measurement 
which  was  discussed  on  an  earlier  page  of  this  chapter.  The  con- 
stancy of  the  relations  of  possible  simultaneous  contact  between 
solids  is  the  essential  precondition  of  all  measurements  of  lengths 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  437 

and  distances.  And  yet  this  constancy  is,  so  far  as  we  can  surmise, 
not  perfectly  exemplified  by  any  collection  of  solids  in  the  universe. 
There  are  many  collections  that  exemplify  it  tolerably  well.  The 
vast  majority  of  things  on  the  earth's  surface  constitutes  such  a 
collection.  But,  if  we  press  our  observations  home,  we  find  shift- 
ing and  shrinking  and  expansion  everywhere,  and  the  very  concep- 
tion of  lengths  and  distances  seems  to  melt  into  nothingness. 

What  course  has  science  followed  in  this  connection!  It  has 
simplified  its  account  of  our  experience  in  a  manner  which  was 
strongly  suggested  by  the  great  mass  of  our  observations,  and  which 
not  only  explained  away  all  past  exceptions  but  provided  in  advance 
for  all  possible  future  exceptions.  This  result  was  accomplished  by 
putting  the  principle  of  measurement  in  a  form  in  which  it  clearly 
transcends  human  experience:  as  a  proposition  involving  a  uni- 
versal existential  negative  and  limited  to  a  single  moment  of  time. 
As  we  have  phrased  it, 

' '  If  A,  B,  C,  D,  and  X  be  any  solids,  and  if,  at  any  moment,  X 
can  connect  A  and  B  but  can  not  connect  C  and  D,  then,  at  that 
moment,  no  T  exists  which  can  connect  C  and  D  but  not  A  and  B." 

The  conditions  laid  down  in  this  principle  are  never  given  in  ex- 
perience. So  complex  a  simultaneity  is  unobservable.  But  ap- 
proximations to  it  are  found.  Many  things  change  slowly,  and 
some  are  changeless  so  far  as  our  available  instruments  and  methods 
can  attest;  so  that  the  duration  and  successiveness  of  our  observa- 
tions is  in  varying  degrees  unimportant.  In  just  those  degrees  the 
principle  of  measurement  is  more  closely  verifiable.  Once  more 
the  law  of  nature  is  found  to  describe  an  ideally  simplified  object :  a 
world  of  hypothetical  solids  which  are  absolutely  rigid  and — with 
exceptions  that  we  have  elsewhere  noted — absolutely  motionless. 

The  assumption  of  the  existence  of  perfectly  rigid  and  motion- 
less solids,  like  the  assumption  of  the  existence  of  points,  is  of  a 
purely  formal  character.  By  no  human  observation  can  they  be  di- 
rectly confirmed  or  invalidated.  So  far  as  the  applications  of  ge- 
ometry are  concerned,  from  the  simple  measurement  of  lengths  and 
distances  onward,  it  matters  not  in  the  least  whether  solids  of  zero- 
length  or  solids  of  absolutely  constant  length  exist  at  all.  By  means 
of  these  conceptions — these  figures  of  speech,  if  you  please — we  are 
enabled  to  analyze  and  describe  the  relations  of  possible  simultane- 
ous contact  between  solids  with  the  greatest  economy  and  practical 
success.  If  these  relations  were  in  practise  altogether  unpredict- 
able— if  the  universe  were  to  our  perception  a  chaos,  in  which 
everything  was  in  irregular  motion — there  would  be  no  measure- 
ment; and  if  the  lengths  which  we  have  to  deal  with  were  seldom 


438  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

negligible  in  comparison  with  the  distances,  there  would  be  no  ge- 
ometry of  points.  The  utility  of  the  formal  assumptions  depends 
on  the  approximate  illustration  of  them  in  the  field  of  actual  ex- 
perience. 

It  may  be  asked,  how  far  the  conclusions  which  we  have  reached 
agree  with  the  well-known  theory  of  Poincare.  The  answer  is  that 
they  correspond  pretty  closely  with  his  conception  of  mechanical 
principles,  while  they  disagree  flatly  with  his  conception  of  ge- 
ometrical principles.  For  one  of  the  striking  features  of  PoincanS's 
theory  of  mathematics  is  that  geometrical  and  mechanical  principles 
stand  upon  an  essentially  different  footing.  The  former  are  con- 
ventions, resting,  not  on  evidence,  but  on  their  superior  conveni- 
ence as  compared  with  other  logically  possible  conventions.  The 
latter  have  a  double  character;  first,  as  empirical  generalizations, 
based  (like  all  such  generalizations)  on  the  approximate  agreement 
of  inexact  observations;  and,  secondly,  as  mathematical  equations 
which  are  exact  and  irrefutable,  but  only  because,  as  such,  they  are 
logically  insignificant  identities.  I  have  tried  to  show  that  geome- 
trical principles  too,  as  descriptions  of  an  ideal  limiting  instance, 
have  this  double  character  of  empirical  generalizations  and  of 
identities.  I  have  tried  to  show  how  this  double  character  arises 
and  wherein  its  utility  consists.  If  I  am  right,  it  may  be  suggested8 
that  Poincare 's  error  arose  from  his  acceptance  of  the  traditional 
view,  that  geometry  is  altogether  prior  to  mechanics.  As  members 
of  the  system  of  mathematical  sciences  this  is  true  of  them.  As 
empirical  sciences  of  nature,  it  is  by  no  means  strictly  true  of  them. 

In  conclusion,  it  may  be  observed — though  the  observation  goes 
far  beyond  the  proper  limits  of  this  inquiry — that  a  very  similar 
account  may  be  given  of  the  general  law  of  the  uniformity  of  nature. 

This  law  has  been  variously  regarded  as  a  self-evident  truth,  as 
an  empirical  generalization,  and  (since  Kant)  as  a  postulate  of  scien- 
tific inquiry — something  that  is  not  known  to  be  true,  and  can  never 
be  proved  or  disproved,  but  must  be  assumed  if  empirical  science 
is  to  proceed  in  the  search  for  truth.  The  first  hypothesis  was  long 
orthodox,  but  has  been  discredited,  not  only  by  reason  of  the  general 
discredit  into  which  axioms  as  such  have  fallen,  but  also  by  reason 
of  the  unclearness  and  inconsistency  of  its  own  many  attempted 
formulations.  The  second  hypothesis  has  therefore  become  attrac- 
tive to  men  of  an  open  mind ;  but  it  has  been  hard  to  see  how  such 
a  principle  as  the  uniformity  of  nature  could  be  established  by  induc- 
tion. J.  S.  Mill's  theory,  that  it  is  based  upon  an  unbroken  enumera- 
tion of  positive  instances,  valid  because  commensurate  with  human 

•  C/.  my  review  of  Science  and  Hypothfgis,  in  the  Philosophical  Review, 
Vol.  XV,  No.  6  (November,  1908),  pp.  634  ff. 


THE  NATURE  OF  SPACE  439 

experience,  will  scarcely  hold ;  first,  because  by  far  the  greater  part 
of  our  experience  presents  no  observable  uniformity,  and,  secondly, 
because  a  great  deal  of  our  experience  presents  what  to  prima  facie 
observation  are  distinct  breaches  of  uniformity.  The  Kantian  type 
of  theory  remains;  but  it,  in  turn,  labors  under  the  difficulty  of 
conceiving  how  the  advantages  of  believing  a  thing  are  a  sufficient 
justification  for  assuming  it.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  moreover,  the 
schools  of  Plato  and  Aristotle  did  not  accept  the  principle,  and  yet 
were  active  in  many  fields  of  investigation.  And  it  is  not  apparent 
why  all  search  for  uniformity  would  be  impossible  except  on  the 
supposition  that  no  irregularity  anywhere  exists. 

Is  not  the  case  similar  to  that  of  the  fundamental  principle  of 
spatial  measurement?  As  has  been  pointed  out  above,  direct  obser- 
vation does  not  prove  this  principle.  Contrary  experiences  abound. 
But  these  we  explain  away  by  saying  that  in  each  case  some  one  of 
the  solids  has  moved  or  changed  in  length  without  our  observing  it. 
The  principle  is  thus  raised  above  any  direct  refutation  by  expe- 
rience. All  possible  exceptions  are  accounted  for.  But  at  the  same 
time  it  loses  its  value  as  information.  Little  good  is  it,  merely  to 
know  that  your  measurements  are  valid  provided  your  measuring- 
stick  has  not  swelled  or  shrunk  and  the  objects  measured  have  not 
changed  their  interrelations.  What  is  wanted  is  a  sufficient  assur- 
ance that  these  things  have  not  happened — to  any  serious  extent. 

Similarly,  when  irregularities  in  the  sequence  of  events  occur 
we  are  ready  in  advance  with  a  universal  method  of  explaining  them 
away.  Either  we  hold  to  the  rule,  but  declare  that  its  working  was 
interfered  with  by  some  contrary  tendency,  or  we  admit  that  the 
rule  is  not  absolute,  but  at  the  same  time  declare  that  an  absolute 
rule — if  we  could  but  know  it — still  obtains.  In  this  sense,  the  uni- 
formity of  nature  by  no  means  includes  or  implies  the  acceptance 
of  any  particular  uniformity.  The  law  of  gravitation,  of  the  inde- 
structibility of  matter,  or  even  of  the  conservation  of  energy  may  be 
only  approximations  to  truth;  but  the  uniformity  of  nature  is  un- 
disturbed. To  believe  in  it  is  to  be  committed  to  nothing.  It  is 
like  the  churchman's  belief  in  the  verbal  inspiration  of  the  original 
manuscripts  of  the  Bible. 

It  has  been  argued  (e.g.,  by  Sigwart)  that  the  principle  of  the 
uniformity  of  nature  is  an  indispensable  premise  of  every  inductive 
argument:  because  we  know  that  "the  given  is  determined,"  we  are 
able  to  prove  that  a  particular  mode  of  determination  obtains.  On 
the  contrary,  I  can  not  see  that  the  general  principle  strengthens  in 
the  slightest  degree  the  argument  for  any  particular  uniformity.  It 
might,  if  we  were  able  to  argue :  ' '  Some  mode  of  determination  exists ; 
no  other  than  this  suggested  mode  is  possible ;  therefore  this  is  the 


440  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

"  But  the  evidence  for  a  law  is  never  so  extensive,  and  it  is 
always  more  positive.  For  this  reason  the  further  argument  that 
is  sometimes  met  with — that  the  uniformity  of  nature  can  not  be 
inductively  established,  because  it  is  an  essential  premise  of  every 
induction — does  not  appear  to  be  sound. 

Men's  actual  belief  in  the  uniformity  of  nature  shows  itself  in 
their  confidence  in  the  continued  operation  of  the  various  empiri- 
cally discovered  laws  of  nature.  And,  historically,  it  is  the  rise  of 
empirical  science  that  has  given  the  principle  its  secure  hold  upon 
our  convictions.  Its  earliest  recorded  expression,  at  the  dawn  of 
science,  by  Heraclitus  of  Ephesus,  was  based  upon  the  simple  cos- 
mological  and  physiological  phenomena  upon  which  scientific  atten- 
tion was  then  fixed — the  regular  cycles  of  the  day  and  the  year  and 
of  the  generations  of  human  life — and  in  particular  upon  that  first 
great  generalization  with  which  science  may  be  said  to  have  come 
into  being:  the  permanence  of  matter  amid  the  multiplicity  of  its 
sensible  forms.  The  various  limitations  which  have  been  set  to  it 
by  ancient  and  modern  thinkers  have,  for  the  most  part,  been  simi- 
larly empirical  in  their  basis,  resting  now  on  the  imperfection  of 
material  things,  now  on  the  consciousness  of  power,  now  on  the  un- 
predictability of  human  caprice.  The  ascendancy  of  the  determinist 
conception  is  a  measure  of  the  success  which  the  enterprise  of 
natural  science  has  met  with;  and,  generally  speaking,  it  is  more 
or  less  marked,  as  habits  of  thought  are  more  strongly  marked  by 
scientific  or  by  religious  and  esthetic  influences. 

As  I  see  it,  the  uniformity  of  nature  is  a  generalization  more  and 
more  strongly  suggested  by  the  extension  of  man's  understanding  of 
nature.  It  is,  in  effect,  an  analytical  proposition,  providing,  as  it 
does,  in  advance  for  all  apparent  exceptions  to  it.  Its  significance 
lies  in  the  fact  that  it  presents  an  ideal  background  upon  which  the 
world,  as  it  is  now  understood  by  us,  may  be  projected,  so  that  con- 
crete programmes  may  thus  be  formed  for  a  better  understanding. 
Just  as  we  have  learned  to  see  things,  not  simply  as  extending,  but  as 
extending  in  space ;  so  we  have  learned  to  see  the  course  of  events,  not 
only  as  exhibiting  certain  uniformities,  but  as  merged  in  a  universal 
cosmos.  The  sequences  of  things,  as  we  perceive  them,  are  often 
erratic,  just  as  the  measurements  taken  with  our  common  yard-sticks 
often  fail  to  agree  by  large  fractions  of  an  inch.  Even  the  most 
refined  observations  with  the  most  delicate  instruments  do  not  reveal 
a  perfect  harmony,  though  the  disagreements  commonly  fall  within 
a  well-established  margin  of  error.  But  behind  the  margin  of  error 
we  see  Nature — and  Space. 

THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA. 
BBTN  MAWR  COLLEGE. 


FISKE  RE-ANTICIPATED  441 

FISKE  RE-ANTICIPATED 

IN  a  recent  number  of  this  JOURNAL  (April  13,  1922)  Dr.  W.  E. 
Wells  points  out  an  interesting  anticipation  of  the  view  of  John 
Fiske  on  the  value  to  the  human  species  of  its  prolonged  period  of 
infancy.  As  Dr.  Wells  remarks,  it  is  hardly  likely  that  Fiske  had 
read  the  English  essayist  of  1834,  styled  V.  F., — the  less  so  as  Fiske 
in  the  preface  to  "Through  Nature  to  God"  expressly  claims  origi- 
nality for  this  contribution  to  the  theory  of  evolution.  But  there  is 
some  likelihood  that  V.  F.  may  have  been  acquainted  with  a  passage 
in  Herder's  Ideen,  of  which  an  English  translation  appeared  in  Lon- 
don in  1800.  The  passage  is  in  chapter  6  of  Book  iv,  and  freely 
translated  runs  as  follows : 

The  first  of  human  societies  was  that  of  the  paternal  household,  a 
society  bound  together  by  the  tie  of  blood,  by  confidence  and  love.  In 
order  that  the  wildness  of  human  beings  should  be  curbed  and  that  they 
sbould  become  accustomed  to  this  domestic  environment  and  intercourse, 
it  was  desirable  that  the  infancy  of  our  species  sbould  last  through  many 
years.  Nature  (by  this  device)  kept  the  group  together  through  necessity 
and  through  tender  bonds,  so  tbat  it  should  not,  as  with  the  quickly 
maturing  animals,  scatter  and  forget  itself.  In  tbis  way,  the  father 
became  not  merely  tbe  sire  but  tbe  educator  of  bis  son,  as  tbe  mother 
had  been  his  nurse;  and  tbus  a  new  element  of  Humanity  was  established. 
.  .  .  We  may  say,  accordingly,  that  man  is  born  to  society:  a  fact  which 
is  implied  alike  in  the  exceptional  sympathy  of  buman  parents  for  their 
offspring,  and  by  tbe  years  of  the  long  buman  infancy.2 

Of  course,  neither  V.  F.  nor  Herder  gave  this  feature  of  human 
growth  the  evolutionary  meaning  which  it  has  in  Fiske 's  work. 
Neither  goes  much  farther  than  to  note  the  far-reaching  utility  of 
the  arrangement;  though  Herder  recognizes,  as  V.  F.  does  not,  its 
place  in  a  series  of  natural  stages,  causally  related. 

In  this  very  partial  sense,  Herder  may  also  be  credited,  I  think, 
with  having  anticipated  the  law  of  recapitulation,  sometimes  called 
Hseckel's  biogenetie  law.  In  opening  chapter  4  of  Book  IV  of  the 
Ideen, — the  thesis  being  that  man  is  in  some  sort  a  composite  or 
resume  of  creation,  and  thus  fitted  to  understand  all  other  creatures, 
— Herder  remarks  that 

Tbe  babe  in  tbe  womb  seems  to  pass  through  all  the  states  tbat  can 
pertain  to  any  earthly  creature.  It  swims  in  the  water ;  it  lies  with  open 
mouth,  etc.,  etc.,  ...  so  man  finds  in  himself  all  tbe  animal  instincts.2 

This  is  recapitulation  without  heredity;  and  hence  something 
quite  different  from  the  theory  associated  with  the  name  of  Fritz 
Mtiller  or  of  Agassiz.  But  it  is  in  a  similarly  truncated  shape  that 

iFrom  Suphan's  edition  of  Herder's  WerTce,  Bd.  XIII,  S.  159. 
2  Suphan,  as  above,  p.  142. 


442  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  germs  of  this  theory  are  commonly  traced  in  the  writings  of 
Erasmus  Darwin,  Lorenz  Oken,  J.  F.  Meckel,  St.  Hilaire,  d'Orbigny, 
and  von  Baer:  and  Herder's  remark  (published  1784)  antedates  all 
of  these.  The  observation  itself  was  probably  not  original  with  Her- 
der, who  was  not  a  physiologist ;  but  as  far  as  I  can  trace  any  percep- 
tion of  the  germ  of  its  later  significance,  the  trail  seems  to  lead  to 
Herder,  and  then  vanish. 

WILLIAM  ERNEST  HOCKING. 
CAMBRIDGE,  MASS. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  Defective  Delinquent  and  the  Insane;  The  Relation  of  Focal 
Infections  to  their  Causes,  Treatment  and  Prevention.    HENRY 
A.  COTTON.    "With  a  Foreword  by  ADOLF  MEYER.    Louis  Clark 
Vanuxem  Foundation  Lectures  at  Princeton  University,  1921. 
Princeton:  University  Press.    1921.    Pp.  201. 
Dr.   Cotton's  book  summarizes  in  simple  form  his  distinctive 
psychiatric  viewpoint  and  methods  together  with  such  broader  as- 
pects of  mental  sanitation  as  would  have  special  meaning  to  the  cul- 
tivated layman.    It  is  a  very  timely  book. 

The  historical  account  of  "insanity"  in  its  social  relationships 
omits  consideration  of  the  not  unfavorable  supernatural  interpre- 
tation sometimes  put  upon  it  in  pre-Christian  communities.  The 
chain  and  straw-bed  period  is  distinguished  as  the  "Age  of  Iron." 
The  early  type  of  hospital,  substituting  the  strait-jacket  for  the 
cage,  represents  the  "Age  of  Leather."  The  standpoint  of  this  book 
is  unqualifiedly  against  restraint,  and  emphasizes  not  less  than  this, 
the  desirability  of  closer  coordination  between  psychiatric  institutions 
and  those  of  general  medicine.  Various  statistics  on  state  hos- 
pitals and  general  population  are  presented.  The  quoted  range 
per  100,000  inhabitants  is  from  374.6  in  New  York  to  83.1  in  Ar- 
kansas. Similarly,  the  number  of  institutional  defectives  per  100,000 
ranges  from  82.9  in  Massachusetts  to  none  in  Delaware  and  New 
Mexico.  The  governing  factors  here  are  probably  the  elaborateness 
of  the  custodial  systems  and  the  complexity  of  social  organization, 
rather  than  inherent  differences  in  mental  health.  This  makes  ' '  raw ' ' 
statistics  of  state  hospital  and  general  population  extremely  difficult 
to  interpret.  A  close  relationship  between  psychiatric  and  correc- 
tional problems  is  emphasized.  The  strictly  physical  nature  of  all 
mental  disease  is  another  fundamental  thesis.  The  tendency  is  to 
discount  hereditary  factors,  and  to  attach  less  importance  than  is 
now  frequent,  to  psychogenic  factors.  The  endocrines  are  regarded 


BOOK  REVIEWS  443 

as  important,  but  apt  to  be  secondary.  "Psychoses  arise  from  a  com- 
bination of  many  factors,  some  of  which  may  be  absent,  but  the  most 
constant  one  is  an  intra-cerebral,  bio-chemical,  cellular  disturbance 
arising  from  circulating  toxins,  originating  in  chronic  focal  infec- 
tions situated  anywhere  throughout  the  body,  and  to  some  extent  in 
disturbances  of  the  endocrine  system." 

This  theory  of  chronic  focal  infections  in  relation  to  mental  dis- 
order is  the  special  contribution  of  the  volume.  The  mechanism  of 
these  chronic  infections  and  their  systemic  effects  form  a  chapter 
highly  interesting,  but  not  for  the  hypochondriac.  Dr.  Cotton  then 
proceeds  to  relate  the  group  of  "functional"  psychoses  to  the 
effects  of  chronic  infections,  identifying  them  with  the  hitherto 
small  group  of  "toxic"  psychoses.  The  essential  feature  of  treating 
such  cases  then  becomes  to  find  and  remove  the  source  of  the  infec- 
tion. For  the  decade  prior  to  1918  the  recovery  rate  found  in  these 
conditions  was  37  per  cent.  Since  this  time  and  as  a  result  of 
treatment  based  on  "  detoxication, "  a  recovery  rate  of  77  per  cent, 
has  been  observed.  Of  another  most  important  toxic  factor  it  is  said 
that ' '  prohibition  has  solved  for  us  the  problem  of  alcoholic  insanity, 
and  has  lifted  a  heavy  burden  from  the  community  as  well  as  from 
the  families  of  those  who  were  alcoholics."  Also  for  the  "nervous" 
or  neurotic  individual  the  importance  of  physical  causes  is  empha- 
sized. Stress  is  also  laid  on  the  morale  value  to  the  patient  of  a 
physical  explanation  of  distressing  or  stigmatizing  mental  symptoms. 

It  is  natural  to  inquire  how  the  establishment  of  such  views  as 
these  would  affect  the  structure  of  psychopathology.  Considered 
purely  in  their  psychopathological  relations  they  are  not  unattractive. 
One  of  the  chief  conservative  bulwarks  against  the  growing  recogni- 
tion of  psychogenic  factors  has  been  the  summary  dictum  that  these 
gave  the  "how"  but  not  the  "why."  Among  those  critically  sympa- 
thetic with  psychoanalysis  one  does  not  always  find  a  categorical 
acceptance  of  the  dynamic  value  of  mental  factors  in  producing  a 
cyclothymic  or  schizophrenic  condition.  A  conception  of  the  present 
type  would  go  some  distance  towards  answering  the  "why"  and 
leave  the  "how"  still  mainly  as  psychopathology  now  formulates 
it.  The  mental  symptoms  of  functional  psychoses  will  remain  what 
psychopathology  now  conceives  them  to  be,  extrusions  from  other 
levels  of  mental  activity  into  the  consciousness  represented  in  overt 
action.  Dr.  Cotton's  postulate  is  that  such  upheavals  in  our  psychic 
structure  can  be  brought  about  by  chronic  focal  infections.  Analogy 
may,  perhaps,  be  had  to  the  process  of  sleep,  which  releases  in  dreams 
"unconscious"  activity  of  quite  as  rich  disorganization,  and  with 
some  topical  similarity  to  the  mental  activities  of  the  psychoses.  No 


444  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

claim  seems  made  that  specific  types  of  intoxication  are  associated 
with  specific  types  of  "functional"  disorder,  in  the  sense  of  syphilis 
with  general  paralysis.  Whether  there  is  any  psychotic  reaction  at 
all  to  the  infection,  and  if  so,  what  the  type  of  psychotic  reaction 
will  be,  appears  a  matter  of  the  individual  constitution. 

Necessarily  there  are  in  a  book  of  this  kind,  many  points  that  the 
layman  may  scarcely  criticize  without  impertinence.  Dr.  Cotton's 
results  have  not  yet  had  sufficiently  wide  confirmation  to  bring  about 
their  general  acceptance  by  psychiatric  authority.  For  such  an  ex- 
tensive testing  of  these  hypotheses,  Dr.  Meyer  pleads  forcibly  in 
his  introduction,  while  plainly  stating  that  the  findings  are  beyond 
what  his  experience  appears  to  be.  It  is  a  distinctly  objective  prob- 
lem, not  open  to  such  difficulties  of  personal  equation  as  apply  in 
the  case  of  psychoanalysis.  Dr.  Cotton's  work  is  on  its  face,  much 
more  confidence-inspiring  than  the  average  presentation  under  psy- 
choanalytic influence.  This  last  has  been  an  outstanding  contribution 
to  the  psychiatry  of  the  past  decade.  The  subject-matter  of  this 
book  is  a  not  less  worthy  challenge. 

F.  L.  WELLS. 

BOSTON  PSYCHOPATHIC  HOSPITAL. 

Sociology  and  Ethics:  The  Facts  of  Social  Life  as  the  Source  of 
Solutions  for  the  Theoretical  and  Practical  Problems  of  Ethics. 
EDWARD  CABY  HAYES.  New  York :  D.  Appleton  and  Co.  1921. 
Pp.  viii  -f  354. 

This  essay  aims  to  present  sociology  as  the  scientific  ethics.  All 
previous  interpretations  are  to  be  superseded  by  "knowledge  of  the 
method  of  realizing  our  human  possibilities  discovered  by  scientists 
and  seers  and  inwrought  in  the  common  sense  and  common  sentiments 
of  a  society."  (p.  5).  Theological  hypotheses  were  based  upon  the 
inadequately  social  concept  of  God ;  a  priori  speculation  scorned  the 
facts  of  human  life.  But  now,  with  the  coming  of  Sociology,  we  shall 
get  away  from  "bad"  philosophy — before  Spencer  and  Comte — and 
view  all  things  in  the  light  of  social  causation.  We  shall  explain 
everything  by  reference  to  the  collection  of  psychophysical  organisms 
and  their  natural  conditioning.  Whereupon,  ethics  is  to  become  a 
natural  science  (p.  511). 

After  setting  forth  the  advantages  of  an  unconditioned  determin- 
ism, the  author  proceeds  to  the  crucial  question:  "What  social 
order!"  "Clearly  no  social  order  can  be  regarded  as  the  standard 
since  every  social  order  must  itself  be  measured"  (p.  111).  As 
answer,  we  are  given  the  hypothesis  (interestingly  American)  that 
the  maximum  of  activity,  the  greatest  quantity  of  human  energy  in 


BOOK  REVIEWS  445 

its  various  forms  actualized  constitutes  the  desired  good.  "The 
object  attained  by  successful  functioning,  whatever  that  object  may 
be,  has  worth  only  if  that  object  itself  be  an  activity  or  a  means  to 
be  used  by  further  activity"  (p.  113).  The  five  classes  of  activity- 
values  are:  (a)  physical  experience,  represented  by  the  comfort 
of  warmth  and  ease,  the  exhilaration  of  muscular  movement,  the 
gratification  of  bodily  appetites";  (&)  esthetic  pleasures;  (c) 
''satisfactions  that  accompany  the  active  exercise  of  the  intellectual 
powers  .  .  .  the  distinctive  delight  of  the  reader";  (d)  social 
experiences;  (e)  personal  satisfactions  (pp.  129-35).  The  reason 
why  Sociology  does  not  aim  to  set  up  a  qualitative  "science  of  val- 
ues" is  "because  the  values  of  life  are  so  accessible  to  ordinary  ex- 
perience, observation  and  inference  and  knowledge  of  them  is  so 
current  in  human  intercourse"  (p.  162). 

One  might,  at  this  point,  be  inclined  to  ask :  "Is  not  ethics  pre- 
cisely such  an  effort  to  determine  qualitatively  a  scale,  of  values  by 
methods  somewhat  more  penetrating  and  exact  than  rules  of  thumb 
current  in  ordinary  experience?"  And  the  question  repeats  itself 
persistently  as  one  continues  reading.  The  sanction  for  any  given 
activity,  according  to  our  author,  is  a  "concensus  of  the  competent" 
with  reference  to  "what  men  in  their  experience  have  called  good." 
And  this  experience  he  regards  as  "incommensurable,"  "indefin- 
able," "indescribable"  as  is  the  color  red  (p.  176).  Yet  somehow 
"social  experience"  teaches  us  "that  conduct  is  right  which  is  the 
condition  of  experience  that  is  valuable."  So  that  we  may 
hope  to  realize  good,  presumably  by  the  trial  and  error  method, 
as  definitely  as  natural  science  lays  down  the  conditions  under  which 
crops  may  be  raised  or  insects  exterminated.  The  new  common  sense 
(by  which  the  author  means  that  which  is  common  to  the  Zulu  and 
Woodrow  Wilson — p.  314)  born  of  advancing  science  will  provide 
extraordinary  progress  somewhere,  though  we  know  not  whither  and 
it  will  be  accompanied  by  "more  stirring  poetry  and  nobler  art  than 
ever  sprang  from  the  cathedral-building  mysticism  of  the  medisevals" 
(p.  208).  But  .  .  .  hands  off  for  all  save  the  natural  scientists !  "It 
(science)  claims  that  the  whole  range  of  phenomena,  mental  as  well 
as  physical — the  entire  universe,  in  so  far  as  it  can  be  known  by  man 
—is  its  field"  (p.  217). 

The  above  will  serve  as  examples  of  the  reflections,  facts,  and 
inferences  which  the  author  presents.  It  confessedly  "skirts  the 
entrance  to  vistas  which  it  does  not  penetrate"  (p.  vii).  With  the 
utmost  generality  and  with  no  endeavor  to  base  his  conclusions  upon 
systematic  "facts,"  whether  of  sociology,  history,  religion,  psychol- 
ogy or  natural  science,  it  seeks  at  once  to  deny  the  most  potent 


446  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

motives  which  have  hitherto  as  a  matter  of  fact  determined  men's 
actions,  and  to  project  a  maximum  of  human  activity  of  all  sorts 
(perhaps  also  animal  and  molecular?)  into  a  completely  mechanized 
world.  Unfortunately  our  author  with  his  "free,  critical,  intelli- 
gence ' '  rising  superior  to  ' '  illusion,  speculation  and  faith ' '  is  yet  un- 
convincing. The  difficulty  is  not  that  one  disagrees  with  most  of  his 
observations.  They  are  not  pertinent  to  his  general  conclusions.  He 
can  hardly  be  said  to  be  aware  of  the  problem  of  ethics,  strenuously  as 
he  combats  all  the  unnamed  deluded,  who  have  hitherto  sought  to 
measure  values  of  human  activity  in  relationship  to  the  most  inclu- 
sive data  obtainable,  data  which,  moreover,  not  a  little  "free,  critical 
intelligence"  has  discovered.  Perhaps  as  his  programme  develops 
he  will  be  able  to  give  us  the  sociological  facts,  statistics,  experi- 
ments, to  demonstrate  how  men  have  no  longer  any  right  to  value  the 
music  of  J.  S.  Bach  or  the  outworn  activity  of  inference  other  than 
that  of  counting  heads. 

JOHN  M.  WARBEKE. 
KOUNT  HOLYOKE  COLLEGE. 

Psychology,  A  Study  of  Mental  Life.     R.  S.  WOODWOBTH.     New 

York :  Holt,  1921.    Pp.  10  +  580. 

In  this  book  the  author  has  brought  together  the  newer  currents 
in  the  science  and  added  them  to  the  older  contributions.  The  gen- 
eral attitude  is  much  influenced  by  the  behavioristic  attitude  and 
specifically  by  Watson's  book,  without,  however,  accepting  the  ex- 
treme statements.  Consciousness  is  retained  as  a  psychological 
category,  and  the  introspective  method  is  not  discarded.  Full 
recognition  is  given  to  the  value  of  the  objective  method,  that 
would  be  the  exclusive  method  of  behaviorism. 

The  order  of  treatment  follows  Watson  as  far  as  he  goes.  Wood- 
worth  begins  with  the  nervous  system,  treated  for  function  rather 
than  for  structure.  The  cuts  are  on  the  whole  schematic.  The  na- 
tive characters,  instinct,  emotion  and  feeling  are  treated  next,  and 
sensation,  attention,  intelligence,  learning,  and  memory  follow  in 
order.  Association  is  treated  after  memory,  then  follow  percep- 
tion, reasoning  and  imagination,  and  finally  will  and  the  self.  This 
means  that  the  plan  is  to  proceed  from  the  concrete  to  the  abstract, 
rather  than  from  the  logically  simple  to  the  complex.  It  will  be 
interesting  to  see  how  it  works  with  the  student.  Each  text  and 
variation  is  an  educational  experiment  and  the  only  criterion  is  the 
pragmatic  one. 

Aside  from  the  arrangement,  the  most  original  part  of  the  book 
is  the  chapter  on  association  in  which  the  nervous  processes  involved 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  447 

are  developed  from  the  conditioned  reflex.  The  conditioned  reflex 
itself  is  reduced  to  the  general  principle  that  when  a  well-developed 
response  is  made  in  the  presence  of  a  stimulus  which  is  only  loosely 
linked  with  that  response,  it  is  transferred  from  the  stimulus  that 
previously  tended  to  excite  it,  to  the  new.  A  number  of  different 
forms  of  association  are  developed  from  this  principle. 

Woodworth  makes  peace  with  the  formal  logician,  by  translat- 
ing the  psychological  processes  into  terms  of  the  syllogism.  To 
the  reviewer  the  discussion  neither  of  the  association  processes  nor 
of  the  reasoning  process  seems  particularly  clear,  possibly  because 
he  is  not  altogether  convinced. 

It  is  interesting  to  note  that  imageless  thought  is  given  rather 
a  more  subordinate  position  than  the  earlier  discussions  of  the 
author  would  lead  us  to  expect.  It  is  made  a  relatively  rare  event 
in  the  thinking  of  the  average  individual.  This  of  course  may  be 
for  the  sake  of  the  student  rather  than  an  expression  of  any  change 
in  point  of  view  of  the  author.  Freud  is  mentioned  frequently  in 
the  discussion  of  imagination  and  dreams,  but  nearly  always  to  be 
refuted.  The  day-dream  and  worry  are  made  concealed  wishes  in 
one  or  two  of  their  aspects,  but  this  seems  to  be  the  only  positive 
influence  that  Freud  has  exerted  upon  the  thought  of  the  author. 

The  book  should  be  a  very  useful  text.  The  style  is  simple, 
usually  colloquial,  sometimes  even  slangy.  It  should  offer  no  diffi- 
culty to  the  student  except  in  a  few  places,  and  should  please  him, 
unless  he  feels  occasionally  that  he  is  being  written  down  to.  At 
times  it  seems  to  the  reviewer  that  more  content  might  have  been 
substituted  for  the  illustration  and  elaboration  that  abound,  but 
this  is  largely  a  matter  of  opinion,  to  be  tested  by  use. 

W.  B.  PlLLSBURY. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  MICHIGAN. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  AMERICAN  JOURNAL  OP  PSYCHOLOGY.  XXXIII,  3.  July, 
1922.  An  Experimental  Study  of  Certain  Initial  Phases  of  Abstrac- 
tion: H.  B.  English.  A  Note  on  Wundt's  Doctrine  of  Creative 
Synthesis:  E.  B.  Titchener.  Synaesthesia  and  Meaning:  R.  H. 
Wheeler  and  T.  D.  Cutsforth.  Series  of  Difference  Tones  Obtained 
from  Tunable  Bars:  P.  T.  Young.  The  Hydrogen  Ion  Concentra- 
tion of  the  Mixed  Saliva  Considered  as  an  Index  of  Fatigue  and  of 
Emotional  Excitation,  and  Applied  to  a  Study  of  the  Metabolic 
Etiology  of  Stammering:  H.  E.  Starr.  Laughter,  A  Glory  in 
Sanity:  R.  Carpenter.  A  Note  on  Henning's  Smell  Series:  F.  L. 


448  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Dimmkk.  Minor  Studies  from  the  Psychological  Laboratory  of 
Vassar  College:  M.  F.  Washburn,  M.  T.  MacDonald  and  D.  Van 
Alstyne. 

LA  CIENCIA  TOMISTA.  March-April,  1922.  El  primer  manu- 
scrito  castellano  sobre  la  vida  y  obras  de  Santo  Tomas  de  Aquino: 
Lius  O.  Alanso-Oetino.  Responsio  ad  "Respuesta  a  un  estudio  his- 
t6rico":  Reginaldus  M .  Schultes.  De  la  accion  social :  Los  errores 
de  monsenor  Pettier:  M.  Arboleya  Martinez.  San  Ignacio,  martir, 
y  el  Cristianismo  primitive  (continuacion)  :  Jose  Maria  Garcia 
8.  Grain.  Actuacion  del  maestro  Domingo  Banez  en  la  Universidad 
de  Salamanca  (continuacion) :  V.  Beltrdn  Heredia. 

REVISTA  DE  FILOSOPIA  (Buenos  Aires).  VIII,  3.  May,  1922. 
Emilio  Boutroux  y  la  filosofia  francesa  de  su  tiempo:  Jose  Ingen- 
ieros.  Los  abogados  y  la  cultura:  Alfredo  Colmo.  La  funcion 
sintetica  en  la  Universidad:  Raul  A.  Orgaz.  Aspectos  de  la  crisis 
actual  de  la  educacion:  Ernesto  Nelson.  Sobre  filosofia  hindu: 
Cesar  Reyes. 

SCIENTIA.  July,  1922.  Les  etapes  de  1'absorption  de  la  chimie 
par  la  physique :  M .  Boll.  Vitalism :  E.  W.  MacBride.  La  fonc- 
tion  musicale  du  cerveau  et  sa  localisation :  L.  Bianchi.  Le  systeme 
capitaliste.  L.  L.  Price. 

JOURNAL  DE  PSYCHOLOGIE.  XIX,  6.  June,  1922.  Signification 
et  valeur  de  la  psychophysique :  E.  Bonaventura.  L'esthetique 
fondee  sur  1'amour:  Ch.  Lalo.  Tendances  et  faits  psychologiques 
(suite  et  fin) :  Fr.  Paulhan. 

Johnson,  W.  E.  Logic.  Part  II,  Demonstrative  Inference:  De- 
ductive and  Inductive.  Cambridge  University  Press.  1922. 
Pp.  xx  -f  258. 

Russell,  Bertrand:  Le  Mysticisme  et  la  Logique.  Translated  by 
Jean  de  Menasce.  (Le  mysticisme  et  la  logique;  L 'etude  des 
mathematiques ;  La  methode  scientifique  en  philosophic;  De  1'idee 
de  cause.)  Paris :  Payot  et  Cie.  1922.  Pp.159.  4  fr.  50. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

In  1920  an  international  society  was  founded  at  The  Hague  under 
the  name  of  Societas  Spinozana.  The  society  has  for  its  object  the 
furthering  of  study  of  Spinoza's  work  and  as  part  of  its  programme 
will  print  annually  a  journal,  entitled  Chronicon  Spinozanum, 
which  will  publish  articles  in  various  languages  on  Spinoza's  life 
and  philosophy.  This  journal  is  not  for  sale,  but  is  given  free  of 
charge  to  members  of  the  society.  Applications  for  membership  are 
invited,  and  may  be  made  to  Mr.  L.  Roth  of  Exeter  College,  Oxford. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  17  AUGUST  17,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


POINT,  LINE,  AND  SURFACE,  AS  SETS  OF  SOLIDS  * 

THE  following  pages  contain  a  series  of  definitions  of  geometrical 
concepts,  based  upon  the  assumed  entity  "solid"  and  the  as- 
sumed relation  "can  connect."  The  precise  meaning  to  be  attached 
to  these  fundamental  terms  could  only  be  made  clear  by  a  set  of 
geometrical  postulates  in  which  they  were  involved ;  but  no  such  set 
will  be  provided.  In  explanation  I  would  say  that  the  object  in 
view  is  not  the  construction  of  a  geometry,  but  the  bringing  to  light  of 
a  certain  limited  order  of  relationships.  It  is  the  possibility  of  a 
geometry,  rather  than  the  geometry  itself  that  is  to  be  exhibited. 

The  formal  explanation  of  the  assumed  terms  being  omitted,  it  is 
necessary  to  give  an  informal  explanation  of  them.  The  "solid," 
then,  may  be  said  to  be  the  space  occupied  by  a  physical  solid.  This, 
of  course,  is  no  definition — the  definition  of  a  term  assumed  as  funda- 
mental is  in  any  case  out  of  the  question — but  a  suggestion  to  the 
reader  as  to  what  the  writer  is  thinking  about.  In  the  same  way  it 
may  be  said  that  the  assumed  solids  are  of  all  possible  shapes,  but  that 
no  acquaintance  with  any  particular  shape  is  to  be  taken  for  granted. 
Professor  Huntington  's  remarkable  system  of  geometry,  in  which  the 
sphere  is  assumed  as  an  indefinable,  will  sufficiently  illustrate  what 
the  system  here  suggested  is  not. 

The  statement,  that  the  "solids"  may  be  of  all  possible  shapes,  is 
to  be  understood  as  subject  to  this  limitation :  the  shape  must  in  each 
case  be  one  which  a  single  physical  solid  can  be  conceived  to  have. 
The  limitation  is  not  absolutely  necessary  for  our  purposes.  With  a 
little  modification  the  series  of  definitions  would  stand,  even  if  we 
admitted  the  possibility  that  a  particular  "solid"  might  consist  of  a 
number  of  wholly  disconnected  parts;  and  without  change  in  the 
definitions  we  might  admit  solids  consisting  of  parts  that  are  in  con- 
tact only  at  points  or  along  lines, — like  a  double  cone  whose  parts 
are  connected  only  at  the  vertex,  or  a  combination  of  two  cubes  that 
have  a  common  edge.  But  no  real  increase  in  generality  would  be 

i  This  article  may  be  regarded  as  an  appendix  to  the  account  of  the  Nature 
of  Space,  published  in  recent  numbers  of  this  JOUBNAL. 

449 


i:.u  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

gained  in  this  way;  and  the  interests  of  simplicity  would  seem  to 
recommend  the  limitation. 

-hall  have  no  occasion  to  make  any  distinction  between  a 
possible  and  an  actual  solid;  every  possible  solid  will  be  treated  as 
actual.  Consequently  we  shall  meet  with  all  manner  of  intersection 
of  solids.  They  will  pass  into  and  through  one  another,  as  physical 
solids  do  not.  It  is  true  that  parts  of  one  and  the  same  physical 
solid  may  be  conceived  as  being  each  a  physical  solid ;  and  these  parts 
may  interpenetrate  to  our  hearts'  content.  But  in  the  case  of  the 
solids  with  which  we  shall  have  to  deal,  we  shall  suppose  that  no 
matter  which  two  of  them  be  considered,  there  is  a  third  that  inter- 
sects them  both,  or  even  includes  them  both  as  parts. 
'  With  respect  to  their  magnitude,  it  is  to  be  said  that  all  the  solids 
that  we  shall  assume  are  finite,  and  that  none  are  of  zero  magnitude. 
We  shall  have  no  occasion  either  to  affirm  or  to  deny  the  existence  of 
infinite  solids.  We  shall  assume  that  there  are  no  zero  solids.  The 
contrary  assumption  might  be  made.  But  it  would  call  for  some 
changes  in  the  definitions;  though  these  would  amount  to  a  less  pro- 
found modification  of  the  system  than  might  easily  be  supposed. 

The  solids  which  we  are  to  consider  are  not  endowed  with  motion. 
They  are  to  be  conceived  as  eternal  beings.  Our  "constructions" 
will  be  literally  no  constructions:  we  shall  but  turn  our  attention 
to  what  was  already  there.  Nevertheless,  the  relations  that  we 
shall  study,  and  in  particular  the  fundamental  relation  "can  con- 
nect," could  scarcely  have  been  suggested  but  by  the  behavior  of 
movable  physical  solids.  More  explicitly,  if  the  physical  solids  A 
and  B  are  at  rest  (relatively  to  the  field  of  observation),  and  the 
solid  C  is  such  that  we  can  manipulate  it  with  a  fair  degree  of  free- 
dom, to  say  that  C  can  connect  A  and  B  would  be  understood  to 
mean  that  we  could,  if  we  wished,  put  C  in  simultaneous  contact  with 
A  and  B ;  and  it  is,  so  to  speak,  the  shadow  of  this  physical  relation 
that  we  shall  assume  for  our  geometrical  solids. 

Yet  there  are  some  noteworthy  modifications  of  the  relation,  due 
especially  to  the  free  interpenetration  of  our  solids.  This  will  be 
made  clear  if,  provisionally,  we  define  the  geometrical  "can  con- 
nect" in  other  terms.  " A  can  connect  B  and  C"  is  to  be  understood 
as  meaning  that  there  exists  at  least  one  solid  X,  such  that  X  is 
equal  in  all  its  parts  to  A,  and  such  that  X  has  at  least  one  point 
in  common  with  B  and  at  least  one  point  in  common  with  C.  In 
other  words,  the  "connecting"  may  be  done  either  by  overlapping  or 
by  external  contact. 

Accordingly,  the  physical  relation  "can  connect"  may  easily  fail 
to  obtain,  where  in  the  analogous  case  the  geometrical  relation  would 


POINT,  LINE  AND  SURFACE  451 

obtain.  Suppose  the  physical  solid  B  to  be  hollow ;  and  suppose  that 
C  lies  deep  inside  B.  Then  no  physical  solid  A,  that  lies  beside  B, 
can  possibly  be  made  to  connect  B  and  C.  But  in  the  analogous  case 
for  geometrical  solids,  if  A  is  only  big  enough,  there  is  no  trouble 
about  its  being  "able"  to  do  the  connecting.  Suppose  further  that 
the  hollow  physical  solid  B  not  only  has  C  inside  it  but  wraps  it 
tightly  around,  so  that  they  are  in  contact  over  the  whole  surface  of 
C.  Then  there  will,  in  general,  be  no  physical  solid  that  can  be 
brought  into  simultaneous  contact  with  them.  In  the  analogous 
case  for  geometrical  solids,  any  solid  "could"  do  the  connecting. 

In  the  course  of  the  development,  a  modified  form  of  Professor 
Whitehead's  method  of  "extensive  abstraction"  is  introduced.  The 
modification  consists  in  the  use,  not  of  the  relation  of  "extending- 
over"  (the  relation  of  whole  to  part),  but  of  the  relation  of  "con- 
taining," in  the  sense  of  not  simply  including  as  a  part  but 
completely  enveloping.  Through  this  modification  the  method  is 
greatly  simplified  and  strengthened.  It  is,  I  believe,  impossible  by 
means  of  the  method  in  its  original  form  to  give  a  definition  of  the 
point  in  terms  of  the  solid.2 

If  containing  is  assumed  as  a  primitive  relation,  extending-over  can 
easily  be  defined.  Thus,  to  speak  of  solids,  "A  extends  over  B"  can 
be  explained  as  meaning :  ' '  There  is  a  solid  which  is  contained  by 
A  but  not  by  B,  and  there  is  no  solid  that  is  contained  by  B  but 
not  by  A."  Hence  the  defining-power  of  the  modified  method  is 
not  inferior  to  that  of  the  original.  It  is,  in  fact,  much  greater. 

However,  in  the  present  treatment  neither  containing  nor  extend- 
ing-over is  assumed  as  primitive,  but  both  are  defined  in  terms  of  the 
relation  "can  connect."  This  mode  of  approach  has  the  further 
advantage,  that  the  conceptions  of  length  and  collinearity  can  be 
defined  without  the  introduction  of  any  additional  indefinable.  A 
complete  conceptual  foundation  for  geometry  is  thus  provided. 

With  the  definitions  two  postulates  are  included,  which  are  of 
special  importance  for  understanding  the  real  significance  of  the 
definitions. 

INDEFINABLES 

Solid. — (Solids  are  to  be  denoted  by  capital  letters.    Different 

2C/.  A.  N.  Whitehead,  The  Concept  of  Nature,  p.  86f.;  also  a  note  by 
the  present  writer  in  the  Philosophical  Review  for  March,  1921.  The  defi- 
nition of  the  point  which  I  once  offered  as  an  illustration  of  Professor  White- 
head's  method  (in  a  review  of  his  "Principles  of  Natural  Knowledge"  in  the 
Philosophical  Review  for  May,  1920)  involves  both  an  error  of  interpretation 
and  a  serious  blunder. 


452  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

rs  need  not  denote  distinct  solids.     Classes  of  solids  will,  till 
further  notice,  be  denoted  by  small  letters.) 
Can  connect. 

Postulates 

Postulate  of  Identity:    If  A  and  B  are  such  that  there  are  no 
d  A',  such  that  W  can  connect  A  and  X  but  can  not  connect 
B  and  A" ;  and,  similarly,  there  are  no  Y  and  Z,  such  that  Y  can  con- 
nect B  and  Z  but  can  not  connect  A  and  Z ;  A  and  B  are  identical. 

In  other  words,  if  A  and  B  are  alike  in  their  capacity  of  being 
connected  with  other  solids,  they  are  identical. 

Postulate  of  Measurement:  If  A  and  B  are  such  that  W  and  X 
exist,  such  that  A  can  connect  W  and  X  but  B  can  not,  then  there 
are  no  1"  and  Z  such  that  B  can  connect  Y  and  Z,  but  A  can  not. 

"NVhen  we  have  defined  the  expression  "longer  than"  we  may 
restate  this  principle  in  the  form :  If  A  is  longer  than  B,  B  is  not 
longer  than  A. 

DEFINITIONS 

I.  If  A  and  B  are  such  that  X  exists,  such  that  X  can  not  connect 
A  and  If,  A  and  B  are  said  to  be  disconnected. 

II.  If  A  and  B  are  not  disconnected,  they  are  said  to  be  con- 
nected. 

III.  If  A  and  B  are  such  that  every  solid  connected  with  A  is 
connected  with  B,  but  not  every  solid  connected  with  B  is  connected 
with  A,  A  is  said  to  be  a  part  of  B.8 

IV.  If  A  and  B  are  not  identical  and  have  a  common  part,  they 
are  said  to  intersect* 

Y.  I f  A  and  B  have  no  common  part  they  are  said  to  be  separated. 

The  reader  should  note  carefully  the  distinction  between  the 
terms  "disconnected"  and  "separated."  Any  two  solids  that  are 
disconnected  are  separated ;  but  the  converse  is  not  true. 

Y I .  If  A  and  B  are  separated,  but  not  disconnected,  they  are  said 
to  be  in  contact. 

VII.  If  A  is  a  part  of  B,  and  if  every  solid  that  is  in  contact  with 
A  intersects  B,  A  is  said  to  be  contained  in  B. 

\Ve  are  now  ready  to  proceed  to  the  definition  of  the  point 
by  the  method  of  extensive  abstraction. 

*  It  is  worthy  of  remark  that  the  relation  of  whole  and  part  can  also  be 
defined  directly  in  terms  of  the  relation  can-connect.     Thus  we  may  say:     If 
A  and  B  are  not  identical,  and  if  there  are  no  X  and  T  such  that  X  can  connect 
A  and  ¥  and  can  not  connect  B  and  Y,  A  is  said  to  be  a  part  of  B. 

*  Here,  and  as  often  as  possible  below,  I  follow  Professor  Whitehead's 
terminology. 


POINT,  LINE  AND  SURFACE  453 

VIII.  If  a  set  of  solids  is  such  that 

(1)  of  every  two  members  of  the  set,  one  is  contained  in  the 
other ; 

(2)  there  is  no  solid  contained  by  every  member  of  the  set; 
it  is  called  an  abstractive  set* 

The  first  specification  shows  that  the  abstractive  set  is  like  a 
nest  of  boxes,  one  within  another;  except,  to  be  sure,  that  whereas 
each  smaller  box  lies  within  the  hollow  interior  of  the  larger  box, 
each  smaller  solid  of  the  abstractive  set  is  a  part  of  the  larger  solid. 
The  second  specification  shows  that  the  abstractive  set  is  an  unending 
sequence  of  solids.  There  can  not  be  a  smallest  solid  of  the  set ;  be- 
cause, if  there  were,  any  solid  which  it  contained  would  be  contained 
by  all  the  solids  of  the  set. 

In  ordinary  terms  we  would  say  that  the  abstractive  set  must 
converge  upon  a  point,  a  line  or  curve,  a  surface,  or  some  combina- 
tion of  lines  and  surfaces.  "We  have  not  assumed  the  existence  of 
such  entities  as  points,  lines,  and  surfaces,  and  so  can  not  use  them 
for  the  definition  or  classification  of  abstractive  sets.  It  will  be 
shown  how  abstractive  sets  may  be  used  for  the  definition  of  points, 
lines,  and  surfaces. 

As  an  example  of  an  abstractive  set,  the  reader  may  consider  a 
set  of  concentric  spheres,  growing  less  and  less  ad  infinitum — never 
reaching  nothingness  but  approaching  it  as  a  limit.  Or,  in  place 
of  the  spheres,  we  might  have,  say,  concentric  cubes.  Again,  we 
might  have  a  set  of  co-axial  cylinders,  diminishing  in  such  a  way  that 
the  radius  approaches  zero,  while  the  altitude  approaches  a  limit 
which  is  not  zero.  Yet  again,  we  might  have  a  set  of  rectangular 
parallelepipeds,  diminishing  so  that  one  dimension  approaches  zero, 
while  each  of  the  other  dimensions  approaches  a  limit  which  is  not 
zero. 

IX.  If  m  is  an  abstractive  set,  the  class  of  the  solids  that  contain 
members  of  m  is  called  an  abstractive  element,  or  simply  an  element. 

X.  If  two  abstractive  elements  are  not  identical,  and  one  logi- 
cally includes  the  other,  the  former  is  said  to  lie  in  the  latter. 

Note  that  different  abstractive  sets  may  serve  to  define  the  same 
abstractive  element.  To  return  to  the  above  examples,  if  the  set  of 
the  concentric  cubes  and  the  set  of  concentric  spheres  have  the  same 
center,  every  solid  that  contains  one  of  the  cubes  will  contain  one  of 
the  spheres;  and  conversely,  every  solid  that  contains  a  sphere  will 

8  This  definition  departs  from  Professor  Whitehead  's  by  substituting  the 
relation  of  containing  for  that  of  including  as  a  part.  There  is  the  further 
difference,  that  the  sets  with  which  he  deals  are  not  sets  of  solids  but  sets 
of  four-dimensional  events. 


454  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

contain  a  cube.    Thus  the  set  of  cubes  and  the  set  of  spheres  determine 
the  same  element. 

On  the  other  hand,  consider  the  case  of  a  set  of  co-axial  cylinders, 
such  as  was  suggested  above,  and  a  set  of  concentric  spheres  whose 
center  lies  in  the  midst  of  the  common  axis  of  the  cylinders.  Every 
solid  that  contains  one  of  the  cylinders  will  contain  one  of  the 
spheres;  but  there  will  be  solids  that  contain  some  of  the  smaller 
spheres  but  do  not  contain  any  of  the  cylinders.  Hence  the  class 
of  the  solids  that  contain  members  of  the  set  of  spheres  logically  in- 
cludes the  class  of  the  solids  that  contain  members  of  the  set  of  cylin- 
ders. It  is  in  such  a  case  that,  in  accordance  with  Definition  X,  we 
say  that  the  one  class  lies  in  the  other. 

XI.  A  point  is  an  abstractive  element  in  which  no  other  abstrac- 
tive element  lies. 

It  will  be  observed  that  the  point  is  here  defined  as  the  class  of 
those  solids  which  would  ordinarily  be  described  as  containing  the 
point — that  is  to  say,  the  point  would  lie  in  each  solid,  but  not  in 
its  surface.  The  formal  properties  of  the  point  as  here  defined  are 
easily  seen  to  be  identical  with  those  of  the  point  conceived  as  an  ir- 
reducible individual. 

The  following  definitions  are  much  less  important  and  increase 
rapidly  in  difficulty.  The  reader  who  so  desires  may  pass  at  once 
to  the  concluding  remarks. 

Hereafter  abstractive  elements,  as  well  as  solids,  will  be  denoted 
by  capital  letters. 

XII.  If  the  solid  A  is  a  member  of  the  point  P,  P  is  said  to  be 
contained  in  A. 

This  use  of  "contained"  will  be  found  to  be  closely  analogous  to 
its  use  as  denoting  a  relation  between  two  solids.  Thus  no  serious 
ambiguity  is  involved. 

XIII.  If  every  solid  that  contains  the  solid  A  contains  the  point 
P,  P  is  said  to  lie  in  A. 

This  definition  may  be  extended  so  as  to  embrace  the  analogous 
relation  between  a  solid  and  any  abstractive  element.  The  present 
definition  may  also  be  stated :  If  the  class  of  solids  that  contain  the 
solid  A  is  logically  included  in  the  point  P,  P  is  said  to  lie  in  A* 

It  will  >be  observed  that  the  relation  between  solid  and  point  (or 
other  element),  which  is  here  defined,  is  closely  analogous  to  the 
relation  "to  lie  in"  subsisting  between  two  abstractive  elements 
(Definition  X). 

•An  alternative  definition  that  is  worthy  of  notice  is  this:  If  no  solid 
that  contains  the  point  P  is  disconnected  with  the  solid  A,  P  is  said  to  lie  in  A. 


POINT,  LINE  AND  SURFACE  455 

XIV.  If  the  point  P  is  a  member  of  the  set  of  points  m,  and  there 
is  a  solid  that  contains  P  and  contains  no  other  member  of  m,  P  is 
said  to  be  isolated  in  m. 

Note  that  if  m  has  but  one  member,  that  is  an  isolated  member. 

XV.  If  a  point  P  is  not  a  member  of  the  set  of  points  m,  but  every 
solid  that  contains  P  contains  members  of  m,  P  is  said  to  be  adjacent 
to  m. 

Consider,  for  example,  the  set  of  the  points  that  lie  in  a  straight 
line  PQ,  between  the  extremities  P  and  Q.  Both  P  and  Q  are  ad- 
jacent to  this  set. 

XVI.  If  a  set  of  points  m  is  included  in  a  set  n,  and  there  is  a 
member  of  m  which  is  not  adjacent  to  the  set  of  those  points  which 
are  members  of  n  but  not  of  m,  m  is  said  to  be  divergent  in  n. 

Thus  suppose  n  is  the  set  which  includes  the  points  within  a 
circle,  those  in  its  circumference,  and  those  in  a  line  tangent  to  the 
circle ;  and  suppose  m  is  the  set  of  the  points  in  the  tangent.  Then, 
except  the  point  of  tangency,  no  member  of  m  is  adjacent  to  the 
set  of  the  points  that  are  in  n  but  not  in  m ;  and  accordingly  m  is 
divergent  in  n. 

XVII.  If  a  set  of  points  includes  no  isolated  points,  and  has  no 
points  adjacent  to  it,  it  is  said  to  be  perfect. 

This  definition  is  substantially  in  accord  with  Cantor's  metrical 
definition  of  the  term.  What  it  really  amounts  to  depends,  of  course, 
on  the  existential  postulates  that  determine  the  universe  of  solids. 
It  should  be  observed  that  a  perfect  set  may  consist  of  several  parts 
that  are  in  no  wise  connected  with  one  another. 

XVIII.  If  a  perfect  set  is  such  that  every  perfect  set  which  it 
includes  is  divergent  in  it,  it  is  said  to  be  a  one-dimensional  set. 

XIX.  If  a  perfect  set  is  such  that  no  one-dimensional  set  which 
it  includes  is  divergent  in  it,  it  is  said  to  be  a  doubly  perfect  set. 

XX.  If  a  doubly  perfect  set  is  suck  that  every  doubly  perfect  set 
which  it  includes  is  divergent  in  it,  it  is  said  to  be  a  two-dimensional 
set. 

XXI.  If  a  doubly  perfect  set  is  such  that  no  two-dimensional  set 
which  it  includes  is  divergent  in  it,  it  is  said  to  be  a  trebly  perfect 
set. 

XXII.  If  a  trebly  perfect  set  is  such  that  every  trebly  perfect 
set  which  it  includes  is  divergent  in  it,  it  is  said  to  be  a  three-dimen- 
sional set.7 

T  While  the  order  of  Definitions  XVII-XXII  is  fixed,  the  statement  of 
them  may  be  conveniently  consolidated  as  follows: 

{has  no   point  adjacent  to   it  f    isolated 

is  perfect  and  includes  no-|  divergent 

is  doubly  perfect  [divergent 


456  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

It  should  be  observed  that  if  the  set  of  all  points  is  three-dimen- 
sional, every  trebly  perfect  set  is  three-dimensional. 

I    perfect 

XXIII.  If  a -{doubly  perfect  set  of  points  is  such  that  it  includes 

[    trebly  perfect 

!    perfect 
doubly  perfect  sets  that  exhaust  its  members  and  them- 
trebly  perfect 

selves  point,  f    continuous. 

include  perfect  set,       it  is  said  to  be  -I  doubly  continuous. 

no  common  [doubly  perfect  set,  [trebly  continuous. 

Tone-dimensional  »        f    continuous, 

XXIV.  If  a  -I  two-dimensional          8.e    ° .       -|  doubly  continuous, 

[three-dimensional  [trebly  continuous, 

fone-dimensionally  continuous 

it  is  said  to  be  a  -I  two-dimensionally  continuous    set. 
[three-dimensionally  continuous 

The  two  following  definitions  are  somewhat  aside  from  the  pur- 
pose of  the  present  discussion;  but  they  are  given  here  because  of 
their  utility  in  serving  to  define  various  types  of  lines  and  surfaces. 

XXV.  If  two  sets  of  points  have  no  common  member,  and  are 
such  that  there  is  no  continuous  set  that  includes  members  of  both  but 
no  other  points,  the  two  sets  are  said  to  be  disjoined. 

XXVI.  If  a  set  of  points  p  (which  may  consist  of  one  point  P) 
and  a  continuous  set  ra  have  a  common  member  or  members,  and  the 
remaining  members  of  m  consist  of  two  disjoined  sets,  p  is  said  to 
divide  m ;  and  if,  further,  no  set  included  in  p  (not  identical  with  it) 
divides  m,  p  is  said  to  divide  m  economically. 

One-dimensionally  continuous  sets  may  now  be  classified  according 
as  they  are  divided  (i)  by  any  one  of  their  points;  (ii)  by  any  one 
of  their  points  except  one ;  (iii)  by  any  except  two;  (iv)  by  any  two, 
but  by  no  one;  etc.  Similarly,  various  types  of  two-dimensional 
sets  may  be  characterized  by  the  number  and  type  of  the  one-dimen- 
sional sets  that  divide  them. 

It  has  become  common  in  recent  years  to  regard  the  line  and 
the  surface — and,  indeed,  the  solid  also — as  sets  of  points.  From 

f  point,  r       perfect. 

•<  one-dimensional  set,  it  it  said  to  be-|  doubly  perfect. 

[  two-dimensional  set,  [  trebly  perfect. 

f     perfect,  f     perfect 

If  a  «et  of  points  is  •<  doubly  perfect,  and  every  J  doubly  perfect  set  which  it 
[trebly  perfect,  [trebly  perfect 

f  one-dimensional 

includes  is  divergent  in  it,  it  is  said  to  be  a  -I  two-dimensional     set. 

[  three-dimensional 


POINT,  LINE  AND  SURFACE  457 

that  standpoint,  the  definition  of  the  one-dimensionally  continuous  set 
may  be  taken  as  the  definition  of  the  line ;  and  the  definition  of  the 
two-dimensionally  continuous  set  (or,  if  it  be  preferred,  the  continu- 
ous two-dimensional  set)  may  be  taken  as  that  of  the  surface.  Pro- 
fessor Whitehead,  however,  has  shown  that  the  line  and  the  surface 
may  be  regarded  as  abstractive  elements.  The  following  definitions 
apply  to  them  in  that  capacity. 

XXVII.  If  an  abstractive  element  is  such  that  the  set  of  the 
points  which  lie  in  it  is  one-dimensional,  it  is  called  a  line. 

XXVIII.  If  an  abstractive  element  is  such  that  the  set  of  the 
points  which  lie  in  it  is  two-dimensional,  it  is  called  a  surface ;  and  if, 
further,  the  set  is  doubly  continuous,  the  surface  is  said  to  be  uni- 
tary.8 

Does  the  figure  8  bound  one  surface  or  two  ?  According  to  this 
definition,  it  bounds  one  surface,  but  that  is  not  a  unitary  surface. 

We  now  proceed  to  some  metrical  conceptions.  The  development 
follows  closely  the  lines  laid  down  in  the  second  article  of  this  series 
(pp.  428-9).  In  some  cases  no  change  in  the  definitions  there  given 
is  called  for;  in  other  cases,  only  the  omission  of  all  reference  to 
' '  chains ' '  of  solids.  The  reader  is,  therefore,  hereby  referred  to  the 
earlier  discussion.  In  the  case  of  the  definition  of  the  sum  of  two 
lengths,  however,  a  more  serious  revision  is  necessary. 

XXIX  (a)  Farther  apart.  (&)  Longer. 

XXX  (a)  Just  as  far  apart.  (6)  Just  as  long. 

XXXI  (a)  Distance.  (&)  Length. 

XXXII  (a)  Greater    (of   dis-       (6)  Greater  (of  lengths), 
tances). 

XXXIII  (a)  Equal    (distance        (&)  Equal     (length     to     dis- 
to  length).  tance). 

XXXIV  (a)   Greater  (distance       (6)   Greater  (length  compared 
compared  to  length).  to  distance). 

XXXV.  If  A  and  B  are  such  that  there  is  no  solid  X  such  that  X 
can  not  connect  A  and  B,  the  distance  between  A  and  B  is  said  to  be 
zero. 

8  These  definitions  are  somewhat  wider  than  those  which  Professor  White- 
head  has  given,  and  I  believe  are  better  in  accord  with  the  tradition  and  the 
needs  of  the  science.  For  example,  according  to  Professor  Whitehead,  there  is 
no  complete  spherical  surface  except  in  the  sense  of  a  set  of  points.  The 
reason  is  that  Professor  Whitehead  is  hampered  by  limitations  upon  the  possible 
shape  of  the  four-dimensional  entities — events — which  his  system  uses  as  its 
basis.  (Cf.  The  Concept  of  Nature,  pp.  lOlff.) 

In  many  eases  hollow  solids  are  required  for  the  abstractive  sets  upon  which 
surfaces  are  founded.  That  is  the  case  with  the  spherical  surface,  for  example. 
Similarly,  for  the  abstractive  sets  upon  which  lines  are  based,  ring-shaped  solids 
are  often  needed.  But  such  cases  offer  no  peculiar  difficulty. 


158 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


This  is  the  relation  that  was  earlier  expressed  by  saying  that  A 
and  B  were  connected.  We  might  define  a  zero-length  as  the  length 
of  a  solid  which  can  not  connect  any  solids  except  those  the  distance 
between  which  is  zero.  But  we  are  not  to  assume  the  existence  of  such 
solids.  If  we  did,  we  should  very  naturally  reserve  for  them  the 
name  of  "points." 


XXXVI.  (6)  If  M,  N,  and  P  are  such  that  X  and  T  exist,  such 
that  the  distance  between  X  and  Y  is  equal  to  the  length  of  M,  and 
such  that  V  and  W  exist  such  that  V  is  just  as  long  as  N,  and  W  is 
just  as  long  as  P ;  and  if  the  distances  between  X  and  V,  V  and  W, 
and  W  and  Y  are  zero;  and  if  no  solid  M'  exists,  such  that  M'  is 
longer  than  M  and  stands  in  this  same  relation  to  N  and  P;  the 
length  of  M  is  said  to  be  the  sum  of  the  lengths  of  N  and  P. 

XXXVI.  (a)  Sum  (of  two  distances). 

In  the  same  way,  we  may  define  the  sum  of  any  number  of 
lengths  or  of  distances,  or  of  both  lengths  and  distances.  The  sum  of 
a  length  and  a  distance  may,  by  convention,  be  regarded  as  a  dis- 
tance.9 

•  Attention  may  be  called  to  the  fact  that  these  metrical  definitions  are 
entirely  independent  of  those  which  precede  them  in  the  present  series,  for  they 
go  back  directly  to  the  indefinable  relation,  "can  connect."  Accordingly, 
it  is  possible,  and  for  some  purposes  it  may  be  advantageous,  to  substitute 
metrical  definitions  of  the  relations  of  whole  and  part,  containing,  etc.,  and 
these  deserve  a  passing  mention. 

(In  place  of  Definitions  II  and  I.)  If  the  distance  between  A  and  B 
is  zero,  they  are  said  to  be  connected;  otherwise  they  are  said  to  be  disconnected. 

(In  place  of  Definition  III.)  If  A  and  B  are  such  that  X  does  not  exist 
such  that  the  distance  between  B  and  X  is  greater  than  the  distance  between  A 
and  Z;  and  if  F  does  exist  such  that  the  distance  between  A  and  Y  is  greater 
than  the  distance  between  B  and  T;  A  is  said  to  be  a  part  of  B. 

In  other  words,  if  no  solid  is  farther  from  B  than  from  A,  and  there  is  a 
solid  that  is  farther  from  A  than  from  B,  A  is  &  part  of  B. 


POINT,  LINE  AND  SURFACE  459 

The  distance  between  a  point  and  a  solid,  and  the  distance  be- 
tween two  points  require  special  treatment, 

XXXVII.  If  the  point  A  and  the  solids  B  and  C  are  such  that  C 
can  connect  B  and  any  member  of  A,  but  for  all  values  of  C',  where 
C'  is  a  solid  and  C  is  longer  than  C",  there  is  a  member  of  A  which 
C'  can  not  connect  with  B ;  the  distance  between  A  and  B  is  said  to 
be  the  distance  which  ig  equal  to  the  length  of  C. 

XXXVIII.  If  the  points  A  and  B  and  the  solid  C  are  such  that 
C  can  connect  any  member  of  A  and  any  member  of  B ;  but  for  all 
values  of  C',  where  C'  is  a  solid  and  C  is  longer  than  C',  there  is  a 
member  of  A  and  a  member  of  B  which  C'  can  not  connect ;  the  dis- 
tance between  A  and  B  is  said  to  be  the  distance  that  is  equal  to  the 
length  of  C. 

The  definition  of  the  between-relation  and  of  collinearity  is  now 
effected  as  in  the  first  article  of  this  series. 

XXXIX.  If  the  points  A,  B,  and  C  are  distinct,  and  are  such 
that  the  distance  between  A  and  C  is  the  sum  of  the  distances  be- 
tween A  and  B  and  between  B  and  C ;  B  is  said  to  be  between  A  and 
C. 

XL.  If  either  the  point  A  is  between  the  points  B  and  C,  or  B  is 
between  A  and  C,  or  C  is  between  A  and  B,  the  three  points  are  said 
to  be  collinear. 

The  straight  line,  as  an  abstractive  element,  may  now  be  defined. 

XLI.  A  straight  line  is  a  line  such  that  every  three  points  that 
lie  in  it  are  collinear. 

Are  there  straight  lines  of  infinite  length?  That  depends  upon 
the  question  whether  there  are  solids  of  infinite  length;  which  in  a 
Euclidean  geometry  is  as  much  as  to  ask  whether  there  are  solids 
that  can  connect  any  two  solids  whatsoever.  It  is  of  very  slight  im- 
portance whether  an  affirmative  or  a  negative  answer  is  assumed. 

A  matter  of  far  greater  importance  is  the  "fixing"  of  the 
straight  line  by  any  two  of  its  points.  This  amounts  to  the  proposi- 
tion, that  if  the  points  A,  B,  and  C  are  collinear,  and  the  points  A,  B, 
and  D  are  collinear,  then  A,  C,  and  D  are  collinear.  In  the  choice  of 
postulates  upon  which  a  system  of  geometry  is  to  be  founded,  this 
is  one  of  the  essential  aims  to  be  held  in  view. 

(In  place  of  Definition  VII.)  If  A  and  B  are  such  that  no  X  exists  such 
that  X  is  separated  from  A  and  such  that  the  distance  between  A  and  X  is  not 
greater  than  the  distance  between  B  and  X ;  A  is  said  to  contain  B. 

The  definition  of  abstractive  seta  and  elements  may  be  left  unchanged. 
The  following  suggests  itself  as  the  appropriate  metrical  definition  of  the 
point: 

(In  place  of  Definition  XI.)  If  an  abstractive  element  A  is  such  that  for 
every  solid  X  there  is  a  member  of  A  that  is  not  longer  than  X,  A  is  called  a 
point. 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

What,  now,  is  the  philosophical  significance  of  this,  or  an  equiva- 
lent, series  of  definitions.  And,  in  particular,  what  significance  has 
the  identification  of  the  point  with  a  class  of  solids  f  I  believe  it  to 
be  considerable,  but  that  it  is  open  to  serious  misinterpretation. 

Recent  theories  with  respect  to  the  relation  between  geometry 
and  mechanics  have  given  rise  to  a  demand  for  the  definition  of  the 
point  in  definitely  experiential  terms.  For  points  are  not  primary 
data  of  experience — if  there  are  such  data.  They  are  never  perceived 
by  us,  and  their  existence  is  never  made  evident  by  any  distinguish- 
able effect,  however  delicate,  of  their  presence.  We  can  not  infer 
their  existence  from  the  perturbation  of  the  orbit  either  of  a  planet 
or  of  an  electron.  They  are  conceptual  constructs;  and  it  is  a 
problem  for  analytical  science  to  exhibit  the  mode  of  their  construc- 
tion. 

i  On  its  face,  the  method  of  extensive  abstraction  is  an  application 
of  "Occam's  razor."  Instead  of  the  point,  which  we  do  not  per- 
ceive, we  are  given  a  class  of  solids  such  as  we  do  perceive ;  and  thus 
entities  are  not  multiplied  unnecessarily.  But  the  point,  as  we  find 
it  in  geometrical  tradition,  is  not  an  altogether  distinct  kind  of 
entity.  It  is  a  solid,  remarkable  in  only  one  fundamental  respect, 
namely,  that  its  length  is  zero.  To  be  sure,  no  solids  of  zero  length 
are  perceived  by  us ;  but  we  could  not  perceive  them  if  they  existed. 
And,  furthermore,  although  we  perceive  solids,  we  perceive  no  ab- 
stractive sets  of  solids ;  and  there  is  no  indirect  empirical  assurance 
that  such  sets  exist — only  suggestive  evidence  that  entitles  us  to 
assume  that  they  exist.  In  accepting  the  abstractive  set,  we  are  as 
veritably  going  beyond  experience  as  in  accepting  the  solid  of  zero- 
length. 

It  may  be  replied  that  the  assumption  of  the  abstractive 
set  is  in  any  case  more  economical  than  that  of  the  zero- 
solid,  because  if  there  are  zero-solids  there  are  abstractive 
sets,  while  there  may  be  abstractive  sets  without  zero-solids.  But 
this  statement,  I  believe,  is  only  superficially  correct.  Just  because 
the  zero-solid  is  an  entity  that  lies  beyond  the  limits  of  any  possible 
direct  or  indirect  perception,  the  assumption  of  its  existence  means 
less  than  the  formal  proposition  indicates.  A  real  point  (as  I  have 
elsewhere  had  occasion  to  urge)  means  no  more  or  less  to  us  than  a 
possible  point.  Hence  the  method  of  extensive  abstraction  has  not 
so  much  eliminated  the  zero-solid  as  it  has  analyzed  it.  The  method 
has  made  us  realize  more  distinctly  than  ever  before  what  the  as- 
sumption of  the  zero-solid  logically  amounts  to. 

Thus,  if  I  am  right,  the  method  of  extensive  abstraction  simply 
gives  us  one  more  illustration  of  Galileo's  great  principle:  that  the 


POINT,  LINE  AND  SURFACE  461 

laws  of  physics — among  which  the  laws  of  geometry  may  here  be 
included — are  descriptions  of  ideally  simple  cases,  which  no  experi- 
ence presents  to  us,  but  which  the  objects  of  our  experience  do  with 
various  degrees  of  closeness  approach.  The  formal  elimination  of 
the  limit  itself,  in  the  case  of  geometry,  and  the  statement  of  the 
laws  in  terms  of  an  infinitely  continued  approximation,  only  brings 
out  with  a  new  clearness  what  their  real  nature  has  always  been.  I 
say  it  does  only  this ;  but  is  not  that  sufficient  ? 

Meanwhile  we  ought  not  to  forget  that  the  geometrical  solid  itself 
is  not  given  in  experience.10  It,  too,  is  the  product  of  an  idealization 
— if  not  individually,  then  as  a  member  of  its  class.  If  we  say  that 
the  physical  solid  is  a  geometrical  solid  and  more,  we  forget  that  no 
perception  assures  us  that  it  has  the  most  elementary  properties  of 
a  geometrical  solid ;  for  those  properties  are  relative  to  the  existence 
of  other  geometrical  solids  which  are  not  physical  solids.  As  of  the 
point,  so  we  must  say  of  the  geometrical  solid  itself:  the  distinction 
between  the  possible  and  the  actual  has  no  place.  To  define  the  point 
as  a  class  of  solids  is  not  to  find  a  place  for  it  in  the  real  world.  That 
can  only  be  done  by  analyzing  those  properties  of  the  physical  solid 
upon  which  geometry,  as  an  empirical  science,  is  founded. 

If  the  point  can  be  conceived  as  a  set  of  solids,  so  the  solid — the 
geometrical  solid — can  be  conceived  as  a  set  of  points.  So  far  as  the 
formal  logical  relations  are  concerned,  there  is  not  a  particle  of  ad- 
vantage in  the  matter,  either  on  the  one  side  or  on  the  other.  Histori- 
cally, as  I  have  elsewhere  urged,  the  conception  of  space  had  to  wait 
upon  the  development  of  the  point.  Psychologically,  the  point  has 
this  advantage  over  the  geometrical  solid:  that  its  very  smallness 
accounts  sufficiently  for  its  absolute  imperceptibility,  and  it  is  thus 
able  to  serve  as  a  middle  term  for  the  thought-transition  from  the 
physical  to  the  geometrical  solid.  Practically,  it  is  the  point  that 
gives  space  its  excuse  for  being.  A  space  without  points  would  be 
little  more  than  an  obstacle  between  us  and  the  physical  world. 

Every  new  scientific  perspective  is  valuable;  and  the  method  of 
extensive  abstraction  has  given  us  a  new  perspective  of  very  great 
value  indeed.  But  we  must  not  let  ourselves  fall  into  the  illusion 
that  the  novel  order  which  it  presents  is  truer,  or  necessarily  more 
fundamental,  than  that  which  has  long  been  familiar  to  us. 

THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA. 

BRYN  MAWB  COLLEGE. 

10  I  should,  of  course,  say  the  same  of  Professor  Whitehead  's  ' '  events. ' ' 


462  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


DOING  WITHOUT  DISTRIBUTION  IN  FORMAL  LOGIC 

IN  the  following  paragraphs  I  shall  maintain  that  it  is  feasible  to 
expound  formal  logic  without  making  any  use  of  the  notion 
of  a  distributed  term ;  that  the  exposition  is,  indeed,  simpler  and  more 
readily  understood  without  the  doctrine  of  distribution  than  with  it. 
Lest  this  should  be  regarded  as  a  recantation,  let  me  remind  anyone 
who  may  have  read  my  article  on  "The  Distribution  of  the  Predi- 
cate, ' '  *  that  I  expressly  reserved  judgment  concerning  the  pedagog- 
ical utility  of  the  doctrine  of  distribution,  while  defending  its 
validity  against  the  destructive  criticism  of  Professor  Toohey  in  his 
Elementary  Handbook  of  Logic.  If  one  succeeds  in  mastering  them, 
the  rules  of  distribution  very  conveniently  sum  up  certain  of  the 
conditions  of  validity  in  conversion  and  the  categorical  syllogism. 
Beginners  in  the  study  of  logic,  however,  find  the  notion  of  a  dis- 
tributed term  exceedingly  difficult,  and  usually  apply  the  rules  in  a 
very  mechanical  fashion.  If,  then,  some  alternative  tests  of  validity 
can  be  devised  which  will  be  easier  for  the  learner  to  understand, 
and  more  nearly  in  accord  with  the  way  in  which  he  naturally  tries 
to  "reason  out  things,"  the  rules  of  distribution  may  wisely  be  laid 
on  the  shelf. 

By  a  slight  change  in  the  customary  order  of  exposition  I  have 
found  it  possible  to  get  along  very  well  without  distribution.  This 
change  consists  in  discussing  the  hypothetical  syllogism  before  taking 
up  immediate  inference  and  the  categorical  syllogism,  both  of  which 
may  then  be  explained  in  the  light  of  the  principles  of  hypothetical 
reasoning.  That  in  a  general  way  the  categorical  and  the  hypothet- 
ical forms  of  reasoning  are  equivalent  is  not,  to  be  sure,  a  new  idea. 
The  traditional  view  has  been,  however,  that  the  categorical  argu- 
ment is  somehow  the  normal  and  natural  form ;  that  the  categorical 
syllogism  should  therefore  be  explained  first ;  and  that  the  hypothet- 
ical should  then  be  shown  to  be  equivalent  to  the  categorical.  My 
suggestion  is  that  in  presenting  formal  logic  to  beginners  this  tradi- 
tional order  of  exposition  should  be  reversed. 

1.  Testing  the  Validity  of  Conversion. — Of  the  various  forms  of 
"immediate  inference,"  the  only  one  which  we  need  to  consider  is 
conversion ;  for  it  is  the  only  one  to  which  the  rule  of  distribution 
is  applicable.  In  my  former  article  I  advanced  the  view  that  a  term 
is  not  distributed  or  undistributed  absolutely,  but  only  with  respect 
to  some  other  term.  Now,  in  inversion  the  subject  of  the  original 
proposition  is  replaced  by  its  contradictory.  In  the  case  of  the 
partial  inverse,  accordingly,  where  the  rule  of  distribution  seems  to 

» This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XVII,  pp.  519-522. 


DOING  WITHOUT  DISTRIBUTION  463 

be  violated,  the  rule  is  really  irrelevant.  "All  8  is  P,"  being  the 
original  proposition,  and  "Some  non-8  is  not  P,"  the  partial  in- 
verse, it  is  true  that  P  is  distributed  in  the  inverse  and  undistributed 
in  the  invertend;  but  in  the  invertend  it  is  undistributed  with  re- 
spect to  S,  while  in  the  inverse  it  is  distributed  with  respect  to  non-$; 
and  from  lack  of  distribution  with  respect  to  8  we  have  no  right  to 
infer  lack  of  distribution  with  respect  to  non-8.  Indeed,  as  Mr. 
Hammond  points  out,2  if  non-S  exists  (that  is  to  say,  if  the  inversion 
of  "All  8  is  P"  is  possible),  P  is  distributed  with  respect  to  non-8 
in  the  original  proposition  as  well  as  in  the  partial  inverse.  If,  then, 
we  remember  that  distribution  is  a  relative  notion,  that  a  given  term 
may  be  distributed  with  respect  to  one  term  and  undistributed  with 
respect  to  another,  it  is  manifest  that  the  rule  of  distribution  is 
relevant  to  no  form  of  immediate  inference  except  conversion; 
since  in  all  the  other  forms, — obversion,  contraposition,  inversion, — 
we  change  one  or  both  of  the  terms  of  the  original  proposition.  In 
the  case  of  conversion,  however,  the  rule  is  pertinent.  Neither  term 
of  the  converse  may  be  distributed  with  respect  to  the  other,  unless 
in  the  convertend  it  was  distributed  with  respect  to  the  same  term. 
Professor  Toohey,  it  must  be  conceded,  is  quite  right  in  maintaining 
that  the  attempt  to  prove  the  validity  of  any  given  process  of  conver- 
sion by  simply  appealing  to  this  rule  would  involve  us  in  a  circle. 
The  rule  of  distribution  as  applied  to  conversion  is  not  an  indepen- 
dent proposition,  but  rather  a  corollary  from  the  demonstration  of 
the  validity  of  the  processes  in  question.  Nevertheless,  admitting 
this  to  be  its  status,  it  serves  as  a  convenient  summary  of  what  is 
possible  and  what  is  impossible  in  the  simple  conversion  of  the  four 
types  of  the  categorical  proposition,  A,  E,  I,  and  0. 

If,  then,  we  are  to  expound  conversion  without  using  the  notion 
of  distribution,  we  ought  to  find  another  way  of  summing  up  these 
results  which  is  at  least  equally  convenient.  This,  as  I  have  said, 
is  afforded  by  the  possibility  of  reducing  our  propositions  to  the 
hypothetical  form. 

The  question  is,  which  of  our  four  typical  propositions  can  be  con- 
verted simply.  Consider  first  the  E  proposition,  "No  8  is  P."  Its 
simple  converse  is,  "No  P  is  8."  "We  wish  to  prove  that  we  can  pass 
from  the  truth  of  either  of  these  to  the  truth  of  the  other.  Now  the 
hypothetical  equivalent  of  the  former  is,  "If  x  is  8,  x  is  not  P" 
while  that  of  the  latter  is,  "If  x  is  P,  x  is  not  8."  And  it  is  evident 
by  the  principle  of  the  modus  tollens  that  the  truth  of  either  of  these 
hypothetical  propositions  may  be  inferred  from  that  of  the  other. 
Consequently  the  first  of  the  categorical  propositions  implies  the 

2  This  JOUENAL,  Vol.  XIX,  p.  127. 


464  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

second,  and  vice  versa.  If,  however,  we  attempt  to  convert  the  A 
proposition  simply,  we  should  pass  from,  "All  8  is  P,"  to  "All  P  is 
8."  Now  these  propositions  are  equivalent  respectively  to  the  hypo- 
thetical, "If  x  is  8,  x  is  P,"  and,  "If  x  is  P,  x  is  8."  But  these 
are  not  equivalent  to  each  other;  for  the  attempt  to  pass  from  the 
truth  of  one  to  the  truth  of  the  other  involves  the  fallacious  prin- 
ciple of  the  "affirmation  of  the  consequent."  Consequently  the  first 
of  these  categorical  propositions  does  not  imply  the  second,  nor  the 
second  the  first.  Therefore,  simple  conversion  is  not  valid  in  the 
case  of  the  A  proposition. 

Granted  the  results  just  established  for  E  and  A,  granted  also 
the  principle  of  the  "square  of  opposition,"  it  is  easy  to  show  whether 
or  not  7  and  0  may  be  converted.  Let  E'  be  the  simple  converse  of 
E,  1'  of  7,  etc.  Then,  if  I  be  true,  E  is  false,  E'  is  false,  and  I'  is 
true ;  while,  if  7  be  false,  E  is  true,  E'  is  true,  and  7'  is  false.  In 
other  words,  from  the  truth  of  7  we  can  infer  the  truth  of  7',  and 
from  the  falsity  of  7  the  falsity  of  7'.  Therefore,  the  7  proposition 
is  convertible.  In  like  manner,  if  0  be  true,  A  is  false,  A'  may  or 
may  not  be  false,  and  0'  may  or  may  not  be  true;  while,  if  0  be 
false,  A  is  true,  A'  may  or  may  not  be  true,  and  0'  may  or  may  not 
be  false.  In  other  words,  we  have  no  right  to  reason  confidently 
from  the  truth  or  the  falsity  of  0  to  the  truth  or  the  falsity  of  0'. 
Therefore  the  0  proposition  is  not  simply  convertible. 

These  results  may  be  stated  briefly  in  the  formula  that  the  simple 
conversion  of  E  is  analogous  to  the  denial  of  the  consequent,  and 
that  of  A  to  the  affirmation  of  the  consequent  in  the  hypothetical 
syllogism ;  while,  as  regards  simple  conversion,  the  case  of  each  of  the 
particular  propositions  is  the  same  as  that  of  its  contradictory. 

2.  Testing  the  Validity  of  the  Categorical  Syllogism. — If  distri- 
bution is  a  relative  notion,  the  rules  of  distribution  in  the  case  of 
the  categorical  syllogism  become,  "Neither  term  of  the  conclusion 
may  be  distributed  with  respect  to  the  other,  unless  in  its  premise 
it  was  distributed  with  respect  to  the  middle  term";  and,  "The 
middle  term  must  be  distributed  with  respect  to  at  least  one  of  the 
other  terms."  These  rules,  as  necessary  (but  not  sufficient)  condi- 
tions of  validity,  proceed  from  the  relations  of  inclusion  and  exclu- 
sion upon  which  the  categorical  syllogism  is  founded.  For  the  sake 
of  brevity  I  employ  the  letters,  8,  M,  and  P  to  indicate,  not  only 
the  three  terms  of  the  syllogism,  but  also  the  classes  denoted  respec- 
tively by  those  terms. 

The  first  rule  is  evident,  then,  from  the  following  considerations : 
(a)  To  prove  that  8  is  wholly  within  (or  without)  P,  we  must  know 
that  M  is  wholly  within  (or  without)  P  and  that  S  is  wholly  within 


DOING  WITHOUT  DISTRIBUTION  465 

M.  (&)  To  prove  that  P  is  wholly  without  8  (or  a  part  of  8},  we 
must  know  that  P  is  wholly  without  M  and  that  M  includes  (at 
least  a  part  of)  S. 

The  necessity  of  the  condition  prescribed  by  the  second  rule  is,  if 
possible,  even  more  obvious.  The  rule  requires,  in  effect,  that  if  M 
is  not  distributed  with  respect  to  P,  it  must  be  distributed  with 
respect  to  8.  Now  suppose  that  M  is  not  distributed  with  respect 
to  P.  Then  so  far  as  our  information  goes,  M  may  be  partly  within 
and  partly  without  P.  In  this  case,  however,  it  is  evident  that  the 
knowledge  that  8  is  wholly  within  M  would  not  justify  any  conclu- 
sion as  to  the  relation  of  8  to  P,  since  8  might  not  be  contained 
(even  partly)  in  the  part  of  M  which  is  within  P.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  knowledge  that  8  is  wholly  without  M  would  justify  a 
conclusion,  other  conditions  being  fulfilled, — for  that  which  is  with- 
out M  must  also  be  without  the  part  of  P  which  is  included  within 
M.  But  in  this  case,  in  the  only  case  in  which  a  conclusion  is  pos- 
sible when  M  is  undistributed  with  respect  to  P,  M  is  distributed 
with  respect  to  8. 

It  is  clear,  then,  that  the  notion  of  distribution,  which  is  irrele- 
vant in  the  case  of  the  partial  inverse,  is  applicable  not  only  to  the 
converse  but  also  to  the  categorical  syllogism.  It  is,  accordingly, 
with  a  certain  degree  of  bewilderment  that  I  read  Mr.  Hammond's 
comment  that  I  am  ' '  quite  right  in  pointing  out  that  the  distribution 
of  a  term  is  not  an  absolute  matter,"  but  that  Professor  Toohey  is 
also  "  quite  right  in  maintaining  that  to  make  a  term  distributed  or 
undistributed  relatively  to  some  other  term  and  to  deny  any  perti- 
nency to  this  distribution  elsewhere  is  equally  to  take  all  value  from 
distribution."  To  say  that  a  rule  or  concept  is  irrelevant  in  one 
specific  situation  is  obviously  not  the  same  as  to  say  that  it  is  irrele- 
vant all  along  the  line. 

If,  then,  we  are  to  expound  formal  logic  without  making  any 
use  of  the  notion  of  a  distributed  term,  we  ought  to  find  a  substi- 
tute for  such  of  the  traditional  rules  of  the  syllogism  as  involve  this 
notion.  This  we  find  in  the-  reduction  of  all  categorical  syllogisms 
to  the  hypothetical  form,  when  they  may  be  tested  by  the  rules  of 
the  hypothetical  syllogism.  Syllogisms  of  the  third  or  of  the  fourth 
figure  are,  of  course,  readily  reducible  by  the  conversion  (or  partial 
contraposition)  of  the  minor  premise  to  the  first  or  the  second  fig- 
ure. It  remains  to  show  with  what  ease  we  may  then  complete  the 
reduction  to  the  hypothetical  form.  Consider  these  moods  of  the 
first  figure : 

All  M  is  P         All  M  is  P  All  M  is  P  All  M  is  P 

All  8  is  M         No  Sis  M  Some  8  is  M        Some  8  is  not  M 

All  8  is  P          No  8  is  P  Some  8  is  P         Some  8  is  not  P 


}»;»;  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Let  us  now  throw  the  common  major  premise  into  the  hypothetical 
form.    "All  M  is  P,"  is  equivalent  to,  "if  £  is  Af,  then  x  is  not  P." 
Let  x  equal  "any  8."    We  now  have: 
If  any  S  is  M,  then  it  is  P 

All  S  is  Af         No  5  is  M  Some  5  is  M         Some  5  is  not  M 

All  S  is  P          No  #  is  P  Some  8  is  P          Some  S  is  not  P 

It  is  clear  that  only  the  first  and  third  are  valid.  Next  consider 
several  moods  of  the  first  figure  which  have  a  major  premise  of 
type  E : 

No  if  is  P         No  M  is  P  No  If  is  P  No  M  is  P 

All  8  is  Af         No  8  is  M  Some  8  is  M        Some  8  is  not  M 

No  8  is  P  No  S  is  P  Some  5  is  not  P   Some  8  is  not  P 

"No  M  is  P,"  is  equivalent  to,  "if  s  is  M,  it  is  not  P."    Again  let 
x  equal  "any  $."    We  now  have: 
If  any  8  is  Af ,  then  it  is  not  P 

All  8  is  M         No  8  is  Af  Some  S  is  Af         Some  5  is  not  M 

No  5  is  P  No  5  is  P  Some  5  is  not  P    Some  5  is  not  P 

Here,  again,  it  is  clear  that  only  the  first  and  the  third  are  valid. 
The  valid  moods  of  the  first  figure  are  then  equivalent  in  each 
case  to  a  hypothetical  syllogism  in  which  the  minor  premise  affirms 
the  antecedent.  In  other  words,  the  first  figure  of  the  categorical 
syllogism,  if  valid,  reduces  to  the  modus  ponens.  We  shall  now 
show  that  if  the  second  figure  is  valid  it  reduces  to  the  modus 
tollens.  We  shall  prove  this  for  but  one  mood,  leaving  it  to  the 
reader  to  prove  it  for  the  rest. 

No  P  is  M  =  If  any  8  is  P,  it  is  not  M 

All  8  is  Af  All  8  is  Af 

No  8  is  P  No  S  is  P 

We  notice  that  the  minor  premise  disagrees  with  the  consequent  of 
the  major.  The  syllogism  is  therefore  valid, — a  modus  tollens. 

No  mood  has  been  examined  in  which  the  major  premise  is 
particular.  Suppose  the  major  premise  to  be,  "Some  Af  is  P." 
Thrown  into  hypothetical  form  this  would  give  us  nothing  stronger 
than,  "If  x  is  Af,  then  x  may  be  P/'  or,  "If  x  is  Af,  there  is  a  certain 
degree  of  probability  that  it  is  also  P."  But  from  a  major 
premise  no  stronger  than  this,  no  trustworthy  inference  can  be 
drawn.  Accordingly,  if  the  major  premise  is  particular  and  the 
minor  universal,  the  premises  should  be  transposed;  while  if  there 
is  no  universal  premise,  the  syllogism  is  invalid.  On  the  other 
hand,  if  there  are  two  universal  premises,  and  with  one  of  them  as 


DOING  WITHOUT  DISTRIBUTION  467 

major  the  syllogism  appears  to  be  invalid,  the  premises  should  be 
transposed;  for  in  a  few  cases  the  syllogism  will  be  found  valid 
when  one  of  the  universal  propositions  is  chosen  as  major  premise, 
although  apparently  invalid  if  the  other  is  taken. 

It  may  now  be  helpful  to  recapitulate  the  steps  which  have  been 
proposed.  In  each  case  as  many  are  to  be  employed  as  may  be 
necessary. 

1.  If  the  major  premise  is  particular,  transpose  the  premises. 
(The  transposition  of  the  premises  obviously  requires  the  conver- 
sion or  the  contraposition  of  the  conclusion.) 

2.  If  the  syllogism  is  of  the  third  or  the  fourth  figure,  reduce 
it  to  the  first  or  the  second,  as  may  be  the  more  convenient.     In 
some  cases  this  can  be  accomplished  most  readily  by  converting  (or 
contraposing)    the  minor  premise;  in  others  by   transposing  the 
premises. 

3.  Reduce  the  syllogism  thus  obtained  to  the  hypothetical  form. 

4.  Test  it  by  applying  the  rule  of  the  hypothetical  syllogism. 

5.  If  the  syllogism  has  two  universal  premises,  and  the  test  indi- 
cates invalidity,  transpose  the  premises,  and  repeat  the  test. 

Not  only  is  it  possible  in  this  way  to  avoid  the  use  of  the  difficult 
notion  of  a  distributed  term,  but  by  applying  the  principles  of 
hypothetical  reasoning  the  other  rules  of  the  categorical  syllogism 
may  be  established : 

1.  In  every  valid  categorical  syllogism  there  are  three  terms, 
and  only  three;  for  otherwise  there  would  be  no  term  common  to 
both  premises,  and  in  the  equivalent  hypothetical  syllogism,  the 
minor  premise,  instead  of  affirming  the  antecedent  or  denying  the 
consequent  of  the  major,  would  be  entirely  irrelevant,  i.e.,  would 
say  nothing  about  the  major  premise  at  all. 

2.  If  both  premises  are  affirmative,  the  conclusion  must  be  af- 
firmative ;  for  it  is  evident  that  the  corresponding  hypothetical  syl- 
logism, if  valid,  will  be  a  modus  ponens. 

3.  If  both  premises  are  negative,  the  syllogism  is  invalid.    For 
the  major  premise  will  then  be  equivalent  to,  "If  x  is  A,  then  x  is 
not  B";  and,  as  the  minor  premise  is  also  negative,  it  can  neither 
agree  with  the  antecedent  nor  disagree  with  the  consequent  of  the 
major. 

4.  If  either  premise  is  negative,  the  conclusion  must  be  nega- 
tive.   Suppose  it  is  the  major  premise  which  is  negative.    Then,  if 
the  equivalent  hypothetical  syllogism  is  valid,  the  minor  premise 
must  either  agree  with  the  antecedent  of  the  major,  in  which  case 
the  conclusion  must  agree  with  the  consequent ;  or  the  minor  prem- 
ise must  disagree  with  the  consequent,  in  which  case  the  conclusion 


468  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

must  disagree  with  the  antecedent.  But  in  either  case  the  conclu- 
sion must  be  negative.  On  the  other  hand,  if  it  is  the  minor  premise 
which  is  negative,  the  syllogism  must  be  a  modus  tollens,  and  the 
conclusion  will  be  negative. 

5.  If  both  premises  are  particular,  the  syllogism  is  invalid.    We 
have  already  seen  that  in  the  first  and  second  figures  the  major 
premise  must  be  universal;  and  there  is  no  way  by  which  a  syllo- 
gism with  two  particular  premises  can  be  reduced  to  an  equivalent 
syllogism  having  a  universal  premise. 

6.  If  either  premise  is  particular,  the  conclusion  must  be  particu- 
lar.   For,  when  the  syllogism  is  reduced  to  the  first  or  the  second 
figure,  the  particular  premise  will  be  the  minor  premise,  and  its 
subject  will  be  the  minor  term  and  consequently  also  the  subject 
of  the  conclusion. 

With  a  little  practice  the  student  will  learn  to  tell  by  inspec- 
tion, without  completing  the  reduction  to  the  hypothetical  form, 
whether  a  given  syllogism  is  valid  or  invalid.  In  general,  if  there 
is  a  universal  premise  of  which  the  middle  term  is  the  subject,  and 
the  other  premise  is  affirmative,  the  syllogism  is,  or  may  readily 
be  reduced  to,  a  valid  syllogism  of  the  first  figure.  If,  however, 
after  the  syllogism  has  been  reduced  to  the  first  figure,  the  minor 
premise  is  negative,  the  syllogism  is  invalid.  For  it  is  clear  that 
an  affirmative  minor  premise  in  the  first  figure  will  affirm  the  ante- 
cedent, while  a  negative  minor  premise  will  deny  the  antecedent 
when  the  major  premise  is  expressed  in  hypothetical  form. 

Likewise,  if  there  is  a  universal  premise  of  which  the  middle 
term  is  the  predicate,  and  the  premises  differ  in  quality,  the  syl- 
logism is,  or  may  readily  be  reduced  to,  a  valid  syllogism  of  the 
second  figure.  If,  however,  after  the  syllogism  has  been  reduced  to 
the  second  figure,  the  premises  do  not  differ  in  quality,  the  syllo- 
gism is  invalid.  For  if  the  premises  differ  in  quality  it  is  clear  that 
when  the  major  premise  is  expressed  in  hypothetical  form  the  minor 
premise  will  deny  the  consequent;  while  if  the  premises  are  of  the 
same  quality,  it  will  affirm  the  consequent. 

My  position  is,  then,  that  the  doctrine  of  distribution  is  valid, 
but  that  for  pedagogical  reasons  it  may  well  be  dispensed  with.  By 
adopting  the  order  of  exposition  outlined  in  the  preceding  para- 
graphs, the  "deductive"  part  of  logic  is  given  a  unity  and  inter- 
connectedness  such  as  is  not  otherwise  attainable.  An  incidental 
advantage — which  has  already  been  hinted  at — is  that  the  forms  of 
thinking  employed  in  the  exposition  are  more  nearly  akin  to  those 
of  other  sciences  and  of  everyday  life.  The  rules  of  distribution 
are  not  likely  to  be  used  outside  the  class-room  devoted  to  the  study 


ROOK  REVIEWS  469 

of  formal  logic.  On  the  other  hand,  the  hypothetical  forms  of 
reasoning  are  employed  every  day,  everywhere.  They  are  '  *  identical 
elements ' '  in  many  diverse  intellectual  operations. 

This  method  of  exposition  is,  of  course,  not  wholly  new.  Mr. 
L.  J.  Russell,  for  example,  approximates  it  very  closely  in  his  Logic 
from  the  Standpoint  of  Education.  But  even  he — whether  because 
of  deference  to  tradition  or  for  some  other  reason — presents  the 
hypothetical  syllogism  after  the  categorical.  And  most  of  the  text- 
books proceed  on  the  assumption  that  the  categorical  type  of  argu- 
ment is  somehow  the  genuine,  true  and  fundamental  type,  of  which 
the  hypothetical  is  but  a  more  or  less  unwieldy  derivative ;  as  witness 
the  desperate  efforts  of  Jevons  and  others  to  reduce  all  hypothetical 
propositions  to  the  categorical  form.  Is  it  not  simpler  to  reverse 
the  traditional  order,  to  treat  the  hypothetical  as  the  generic  type, 
of  which  the  categorical  is  a  specific  modification?  There  may  be 
some  recondite  objection  to  this  procedure;  but  until  it  is  pointed 
out,  the  simpler  organization  of  the  subject-matter  appears  to  be 
preferable. 

RAY  H.  DOTTERER. 

PENNSYLVANIA  STATE  COLLEGE. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Human  Nature  and  Conduct:  An  Introduction  to  Social  Psychology. 

John  Dewey.     Henry  Holt  &  Co.     1922.     Pp.  336. 

If  pragmatism  is  not  the  sanctification  of  commercialism,  and 
of  course  no  one  soberly  supposes  that  it  is,  it  may  none  the  less  be 
the  intellectual  accompaniment  of  the  machine  process — of  industrial 
rather  than  commercial  civilization.  There  is  nothing  incompatible, 
so  at  least  Veblen  asserts,  between  a  high  commercialism  and  the 
densest  animism — indeed,  quite  the  contrary.  A  well-matured  ma- 
chine technique,  however,  presupposes  and  directly  cultivates  the 
scientific  temper.  The  reconstruction  of  philosophy  in  modern  times 
must  be  regarded  as  a  refunding  operation  through  which  philosophy 
is  being  merged  with  modern  science.  This  process  began  with  the 
starry  heavens  above;  Professor  Dewey 's  latest  book  suggests  the 
speculation  that  its  consummation  may  be  the  moral  law  within. 

Naturally  the  development  of  empiricism  from  Bacon  and  Hobbes 
to  the  present  revolt  against  Hegelian  absolutism  has  not  been  with- 
out incident:  that  wave  of  absolutism  in  the  nineteenth  century  is 
its  chief  incident.  The  unsurpassed  scientific  objectivity  of  Hume 
and  Kant  was  swamped  in  the  decades  that  brought  the  Holy 
Alliance  and  the  Wesleyan  revival  by  a  general  resumption  of  the 


470  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

medieval  habit  of  mind.  And  through  the  exigencies  of  university 
organization  this  habit  has  persisted  well  into  the  twentieth  century 
so  that  a  world  which  has  become  thoroughly  trained  in  the  scien- 
tific bent  can  contemplate  the  persistence  at  the  centers  of  its  intellec- 
tual life  of  a  tradition  which,  conceiving  the  human  soul  in  the  spirit 
of  the  medieval  church,  proceeds  to  impute  its  characteristics  to  the 
universe  at  large,  to  the  utter  neglect  if  not  the  denial  of  the  con- 
trary scientific  preconceptions  of  all  the  rest  of  the  world. 

The  presence  and  continued  (though  weakening)  vigor  of  this 
tradition  accounts  for  the  posture  of  contemporary  empiricism,  as 
distinguished  from  that  of  the  period  which  the  course  books  call 
"modern."  The  modern  philosophy  of  Bacon,  or  even  of  Descartes, 
represented  the  first  onslaught  of  physics  and  mathematics  upon  the 
glorified  animism  of  medieval  theology — of  the  solar  system  upon 
the  soular  system.  Contemporary  instrumentalism,  speaking  in  a 
world  now  overwhelmingly  scientific,  is  directed  against  the  last 
stand  of  animism  (for  McDougall  is  right  in  identifying  mentalism 
as  animism)  in  the  field  of  human  behavior.  The  most  bitterly 
contested  issues  in  contemporary  philosophy  (arising  between  ideal- 
ism and  pragmatism)  are  psychological  issues.  The  first  great 
breach  in  the  tradition  of  absolutism  was  made  by  a  psychologist 
trained  in  medicine  and  physiology;  Professor  Dewey's  most  dis- 
tinctive achievement  also  is  behaviorism.  The  Essays  in  Experi- 
mental Logic,  so  metaphysical  in  tone,  have  as  their  principal  burden 
the  maintenance  of  the  psychological  (behaviorist)  assumption  that 
thinking  is  a  part  of  human  behavior  and  must  be  treated  as  such 
against  a  school  which  rejoices  first  to  abstract  thinking  from  the 
rest  of  the  universe  and  then  to  bring  the  universe  over  into  thought. 
Similarly  the  educational  principles  of  Democracy  and  Education, 
etc.,  derive  from  the  behaviorist  assumption  on  the  nature 
of  education:  the  behavior  of  children,  intellectual  and  other- 
wise, can  be  guided  successfully  only  in  such  an  environment  as  pro- 
vokes the  desired  responses  and  allows  them  to  integrate  into  habits. 

Perhaps  it  is  owing  to  his  absorption  in  educational  theory  that 
Professor  Dewey's  own  interest  in  the  study  of  behavior  and  the  at- 
tack upon  animism  has  become  increasingly  social  and  has  now  re- 
sulted in  a  volume  of  lectures  on  social  psychology.  Perhaps  it  is 
also  due  to  his  large  preoccupation  with  public  affairs  during  the 
war  and  the  peace — since  the  time  of  Randolph  Bourne's  devoted 
though  "savage  indignation"  that  he  was  not  then  "out  in  the  arena 
of  the  concrete,  himself  interpreting  current  life. ' ' *  Probably  a 
deeper  reason  lies  in  the  character  of  social  psychology. 

i  Nev  Bepvblic,  March  13,  1915. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  471 

The  vital  issues  of  behaviorism  are  at  this  moment  to  be  found 
in  social  psychology.  The  inevitable  extension  of  the  experimental 
technique  from  biology  to  psychology  at  first  involved  no  abatement 
of  mentalism.  Certain  mental  states  seemed  to  be  susceptible  to  the 
technique,  which  was  accordingly  applied — particularly  of  course 
to  sensations,  since  the  sense  organs  are  the  most  accessible.  In  the 
course  of  time  the  physiological  character  of  both  investigations  and 
data  has  come  to  be  recognized  and  a  rapprochement  established  be- 
tween neurology  and  psychology,  until  now  so  large  a  proportion  of 
the  actual  labors  of  all  the  psychologists  is  experimental  that  the 
distinction  between  behaviorists  and  others  seems  largely  a  matter  of 
terminology.  Simultaneously,  however,  has  come  a  quite  general 
sense  that  mentalism,  unwittingly  pushed  out  of  individual  psychol- 
ogy by  the  experimental  technique,  can  make  a  stand  on  instinct  in 
social  behavior.  Particular  reactions  may  be  experimentally  reduci- 
ble to  neurological  (or  glandular)  terms;  general  tendencies  may 
still  be  couched  in  terms  as  mystical  as  one  could  wish.  The  spirit 
world,  excluded  from  the  reflex  arc,  the  tropism,  and  the  hormone, 
may  still  make  its  entrance  through  the  magic  potencies  of  instinct, 
precisely  as  it  once  did  through  Descartes 's  pineal  gland.  The  Car- 
tesian dualism  of  mystical  and  scientific  principles  in  human  behavior 
is  today  the  dualism  of  instinct  and  habit.  To  be  sure,  general  inter- 
est in  the  problem  has  shifted  from  theology  to  sociology;  but  the 
issues  remain  unchanged.2 

Upon  this  problem  Professor  Dewey  now  takes  his  stand  as  un- 
compromisingly as  in  his  most  polemical  metaphysics.  Human  Na- 
ture and  Conduct  presents  Dewey 's  theory  of  the  organization  of 
human  behavior,  in  individuals  and  communities,  by  habit  and 
custom.  Its  fundamental  postulate  is  the  abandonment  of  the  old 
individual  psychology  of  separate  and  independent  minds  by  which 
mind  has  been  conceived  as  a  mysterious  intruder,  or  a  mysterious 
parallel  accomplishment  of  the  natural  world  (pp.  84,  5).  The  cor- 
responding antithetical  assumption  that  is  postulated  in  its  place 
is  the  one  which  has  been  much  more  familiar  hitherto  in  anthro- 
pology than  in  psychology.  There  the  formula  is:  Omnis  cidtura 
ex  cultura.  "The  problem  of  social  psychology,"  writes  Dewey,  "is 
not  how  either  individual  or  collective  mind  forms  social  groups 
and  customs,  but  how  different  customs,  establishing  interacting 
arrangements,  form  and  nurture  different  minds"  (p.  63).  "We 

2  Professor  Dewey  emphasizes  this  shift  of  interest,  attributing  it  to  the 
general  "decline  in  the  authority  of  social  oligarchy"  (p.  3),  and  interest  in 
"doing  away  with  old  institutions"  (p.  93).  Of  course  magic  potencies  may 
be  displayed  on  both  sides  of  such  controversies.  Carleton  Parker  drew  on 
McDougall's  instincts  in  his  defense  of  the  I.  W.  W.,  though  MeDougall  reserves 
them  for  God,  for  country,  and  for  home. 


472  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

often  fancy  that  institutions,  social  customs,  collective  habit,  have 
been  formed  by  the  consolidation  of  individual  habits.  In  the  main 
this  supposition  is  false  to  fact.  .  .  .  Customs  persist  because  indi- 
viduals form  their  personal  habits  under  conditions  set  by  prior 
customs"  (p.  58).  That  is,  the  indispensable  condition  of  the 
organization  of  behavior  is  preexisting  organized  behavior. 

Such  a  theory  of  conduct  has  conspicuous  implications  for  ethics. 
Professor  Dewey  accepts  them  at  once,  and  accordingly  makes 
moral  conduct  the  chief  subject  of  his  analysis  throughout  the  book. 
For  such  a  theory  of  behavior  as  this,  "morals  mean  customs,  folk- 
ways, established  collective  habits.  This  is  a  commonplace  of  the 
anthropologist,  though  the  moral  theorist  generally  suffers  from  an 
illusion  that  his  own  place  and  day  is,  or  ought  to  be,  an  exception. 
But  always  and  everywhere  customs  supply  the  standards  for 
personal  activities"  (p.  75).  By  accepting  the  hardly  more  than 
Darwinian  hypothesis  that  the  facts  of  man  are  continuous  with  those 
of  the  rest  of  nature  we  can  ally  ethics  with  physics  and  biology; 
by  accepting  the  anthropological  dogma  of  the  continuity  of  all  hu- 
man activity  we  can  link  ethics  with  history,  sociology,  jurispru- 
dence, and  economics  (p.  12).  Even  moral  philosophy  can  be  as- 
similated to  modern  science! 

The  three  lectures,  on  habit,  impulse,  and  intelligence,  which 
make  up  the  bulk  of  the  book,  seek  to  indicate  how  this  may  be 
done.  They  are  an  introduction  not  so  much  to  the  subject  of  so- 
cial psychology,  or  of  ethics,  as  to  the  problems :  not  a  syllabus  out- 
line of  a  fully  developed  science  but  a  preliminary  statement  of  the 
presuppositions  upon  which  a  science  may  be  developed.  Habit  is 
the  framework  and  custom  the  content  of  behavior.  Impulse  is  the 
propelling,  energy-releasing  force  behind  all  activity — not  in  the 
form  of  the  familiar  instincts  (there  are  no  separate  instincts),  but 
as  a  tremendous  multiplicity  of  exceedingly  circumscribed  reac- 
tions to  specific  stimuli.8  They  require  to  be  organized  by  habit 
into  modes  of  behavior  and  only  thus  assume  form  as  the  activity 
of  civilized  man.  And  if  we  do  not  know,  at  least  we  know  how 
with  our  habits.  Knowledge  lives  in  the  muscles,  trained  muscles, 
not  in  consciousness.  Thought  is  the  interruption,  the  clash,  the 
readjustment  of  habits. 

•  Professor  Dewey  give*  the  reader  every  reason  to  suppose  that  the  impulses 
which  he  retains  as  the  basis  of  all  behavior  after  the  rejection  of  "separate 
instincts"  are  the  reflexes  and  tropisms  and  so  on,  familiar  to  the  neurologist. 
For  some  reason,  to  my  mind  highly  questionable,  he  refrains  from  any  direct 
assertion  to  this  effect  either  in  the  form  of  a  reference  to  the  literature  of 
neurology  or  by  the  use  of  identifying  technical  words.  Perhaps  neither  could 
be  done  in  lectures ;  but  as  an  "  Introduction ' '  the  book  ought  to  introduce. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  473 

All  this  becomes  concrete  when  it  is  applied  to  the  problem  of 
conduct.  Morality  is  custom-organized,  habitual  behavior;  there 
are  no  bad  habits  but  custom  makes  them  so.  No  moral  order  is 
based  on  instinctive,  eternally  unalterable  behavior,  nor  can  moral 
order  result  from  /the  abrogation  of  all  organizing  conventions. 
Morality  is  the  ordering  of  habit  by  intelligence.  Rejecting  all 
ethical  principles  that  would  identify  morality  with  some  special 
type  of  impulse  or  experience,  Professor  Dewey  describes  it  essenti- 
ally as  Kant  did — as  order.  "  Intelligence  is  concerned  with  fore- 
seeing the  future  so  that  action  may  have  order  and  direction"  (p. 
238).  Morality  is  the  outcome  of  practical  reason. 

And  then — strangely  enough,  for,  from  the  Outlines  of  Ethics 
(published  at  Ann  Arbor  in  1891)  to  the  present  work,  Dewey  has 
devoted  more  space  to  the  criticism  of  Kant  than  of  any  other  phi- 
losopher, and  always  for  this  very  peculiarity — he  recommends  in- 
telligence ! 

This  is  no  new  thing,  of  course.  "Creative  intelligence"  has 
been  as  much  a  slogan  as  a  description  among  pragmatists  since 
James.  Professor  Dewey 's  constant  insistence  in  his  philosophical 
writing  upon  the  functional,  experimental  character  of  the  think- 
ing process  seems  to  express  a  very  deep-lying  and  in  the  end  hyper- 
logical  belief  in  its  efficacy;  while  in  the  magazine  articles  his  en- 
thusiasm for  intelligence  approximates  that  of  the  revivalist.* 

It  is  not  my  object  here  to  give  Kant  an  inning  against  his  most 
insistent  critic,  nor  even  to  assert  the  futility  of  advising  the  world 
to  be  intelligent,  to  organize  its  habits  flexibly,  and  all  that.  Pro- 
fessor Dewey  has  made  the  best  possible  case  against  an  ethics  of 
mandatory  principles  in  this  book.5  Simply  to  note  that  the  cate- 
gorical imperative  appears  from  chapter  to  chapter  is  interesting, 
however.6  In  his  famous  essay  on  the  influence  of  Darwin  on  phi- 
losophy Professor  Dewey  summarized  as  follows:  "No  one  can 

*  E.g.,  "The  American  Intellectual  Frontier,"  New  Republic,  May  10,  1922. 

5  E.g.,  p.  27.  ' '  Keeently  a  friend  remarked  to  me  that  there  was  one 
superstition  current  among  even  cultivated  persons.  They  suppose  that  if  one 
is  told  what  to  do,  if  the  right  end  is  pointed  out  to  them,  all  that  is  required 
in  order  to  bring  about  the  right  act  is  will  or  wish  oa  the  part  of  the  one  who 
is  to  act."  Etc.,  etc. 

e  An  individual  ' '  can,  if  he  will,  intelligently  adapt  customs  to  traditions ' ' 
(p.  75).  "The  most  precious  part  of  plasticity  consists  in -ability  to  form 
habits  of  independent  judgment  and  of  inventive  initiation"  (p.  97).  "In 
learning  habits  it  is  possible  for  men  to  learn  the  habit  of  learning.  Then 
betterment  becomes  a  conscious  principle  of  life"  (p.  105).  "The  moral  is 
to  develop  conscientiousness,  ability  to  judge  the  significance  of  what  we  are 
doing.  .  .  .  Therefore  the  important  thing  is  the  fostering  of  those  habits  and 
impulses  which  lead  to  a  broad,  just,  sympathetic  survey  of  situations"  (p.  207). 


474  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

fairly  deny  that  at  present  there  are  two  effects  of  the  Darwinian 
mode  of  thinking.  On  the  one  hand  there  are  making  many  sincere 
and  vital  efforts  to  revise  our  traditional  philosophic  conceptions 
in  accordance  with  its  demands.  On  the  other  hand,  there  is  as  defi- 
nitely a  recrudescence  of  absolutist  philosophies."  Is  it  certain 
that  the  two  will  be  wholly  separate?  Perhaps  the  gospel  of  sci- 
ence contains  its  own  absolutism,  its  own  rationalism,  its  own  infi- 
nite,7 its  "appeal  through  experience  to  something  that  essentially 
goes  beyond  experience" — beyond,  that  is  to  say,  the  coolly  skeptical- 
experimental  observations  of  the  scientist. 

Without  doubt  this  is  a  lapse  in  logic.  Yet  for  the  discriminat- 
ing reader  it  may  serve  to  make  the  book  a  human  document  with- 
out materially  affecting  the  clarity  of  the  issues.  Life  is  a  continu- 
ous lapse  of  logic,  and  this  book  seems  to  me  rather  more  alive,  more 
directly  and  humanly  expressive,  than  any  other  that  Professor 
Dewey  has  yet  written.  This  is  yet  another  reason  why,  though  it 
is  an  introduction,  it  is  not  a  syllabus.  One  feels  in  reading  that 
the  whole  range  of  interest  of  a  most  flexible  mind  is  being  played 
upon  the  text.  The  harmonies  are  rich  and  varied,  and  sonata-form 
gets  lost  in  their  depths.  Indeed,  the  organization  of  the  book  is 
very  loose — much  less  rigid  even  than  the  analytical  table  augurs. 
In  general  it  follows  the  three-fold  division  indicated  above;  but 
apart  from  that  the  ideas  flow  down  their  natural  and  broken  course 
rather  than  through  the  concreted  channel  of  a  pre-determined 
order. 

The  course  provides  many  interesting  moments.  "All  habits 
are  demands  for  certain  kinds  of  activity;  and  they  constitute  the 
self.  In  any  intelligible  sense  of  the  word  will,  they  are  will"  (p. 
25).  "For  will  means,  in  the  concrete,  habits;  and  habits  incorpo- 
rate an  environment  within  themselves.  They  are  adjustments  of 
the  environment,  not  merely  to  it"  (p.  52).  "Were  it  not  for  the 
continued  operation  of  all  habits  in  every  act,  no  such  thing  as 
character  could  exist.  There  would  be  simply  a  bundle,  an  untied 
bundle  at  that,  of  isolated  acts.  Character  is  the  interpenetration 
of  habits"  (p.  38).  "Why  have  men  become  so  attached  to  fixed, 
eternal  endst  Why  is  it  not  universally  recognized  that  an  end  is 
a  device  of  intelligence  in  guiding  action,  instrumental  to  freeing 
and  harmonizing  troubled  and  divided  tendencies?  .  .  .  Ends  are, 
in  fact,  literally  endless,  forever  coming  into  existence  as  new  ac- 
tivities occasion  new  consequences"  (pp.  231-2).  "As  we  account 

'"Beligion,  aa  a  sense  of  the  whole,  is  the  most  individualized  of  all 
thing*  ....  Instead  of  marking  the  freedom  and  peace  of  the  individual 
as  a  member  of  an  infinite  whole,  it  has  been  ...  "  (p.  331). 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  475 

for  war  by  pugnacity,  for  the  capitalistic  system  by  the  necessity  of 
an  incentive  of  gain  to  stir  ambition  and  effort,  so  we  account  for 
Greece  by  power  of  esthetic  observation,  Rome  by  administrative 
ability,  the  middle  ages  by  interest  in  religion,  and  so  on.  We  have 
constructed  an  elaborate  political  zoology  as  mythical  and  not 
nearly  as  poetic  as  the  other  zoology  of  phrenixes,  griffins  and  uni- 
corns" (p.  111).  " Current  democracy  acclaims  success  more  bois- 
terously than  do  other  social  forms,  and  surrounds  failure  with  a 
more  reverberating  train  of  echoes.  But  the  prestige  thus  given 
excellence  is  largely  adventitious.  The  achievement  of  thought  at- 
tracts others  not  so  much  intrinsically  as  because  of  an  eminence 
due  to  multitudinous  advertising  and  a  swarm  of  imitators"  (p. 
66).  "It  is  only  by  accident  that  the  separate  and  endowed 
'thought'  of  professional  thinkers  leaks  out  into  action  and  affects 
custom"  (pp.  68-9).  "...  think  of  the  insolent  coercions,  the  in- 
sinuating briberies,  the  pedagogic  solemnities  by  which  the  fresh- 
ness of  youth  can  be  faded  and  its  vivid  curiosities  dulled.  Educa- 
tion becomes  the  art  of  taking  advantage  of  the  helplessness  of  the 
young;  the  forming  of  habits  becomes  a  guarantee  for  the  mainte- 
nance of  hedges  of  custom"  (p.  64). 

In  short  this  is  the  most  eminently  readable  and  quotable  book 
Professor  Dewey  has  written.8  But  it  is  not  a  "text";  it  will  not 
suit  the  orderly  and  sterile  mind  of  the  efficient  teacher.  And  it 
will  be  a  hard  book  for  professional  attackers  and  defenders  of  the 
pragmatic  faith,  for  the  word  "pragmatism"  occurs  only  in  the  in- 
dex, the  word  "  instrumentalism "  not  at  all. 

C.  E.  AYRES. 
AMHEEST  COLLEGE. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

REVISTA  DE  PSIQUIATRIA  Y  DISCIPLINAS  CONEXAS  (Lima).  IV,  2. 
April,  1922.  Los  Mitos  Medicos  peruanos:  Hermilio  Valdizan  y 
Angel  Maldonado.  Confusion  mental  en  la  encefalitis  epidemica: 
Max.  Gonzales  Olaechea.  El  Mongolismo:  E.  8.  Guzman  Barron. 
Reaccion  subepidermica  a  la  adrenal  ina  como  metodo  de  exploracion 
del  sistema  nervioso  simpatico:  Dclfin  C.  Espino.  La  negacion  de 
la  paternidad  como  sintoma  psicosico  (conclusion)  :  Honorio  F. 
Delgado.  Tratameinto  de  la  epilepsia  por  el  luminal:  Honorio  F. 
Delgado. 

s  This  in  spite  of  the  lack  of  tonality  of  its  author 's  style — frequently 
noted  by  reviewers — which  allows  him  to  use  the  jarring  form  "morals  is," 
and  to  pass  over  slips  in  construction  like  that  on  p.  22,  line  16,  or  the  "one- 
them  "  of  a  sentence  quoted  above. 


476  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

REVUE  PHILOSOPHIQUE.  XLVII,  5-6.  May-June,  1922.  Le 
renouvellement  des  conceptions  atomistiques:  L.  Brunschvicg. 
William  James  d'apres  sa  correspondence:  J.  l\V//»/.  L'ennui  mor- 
bide:  L.  Dupuit.  La  psychoanalyse  et  le  probleme  de  1  'inconscient, 
II :  A.  Ombre dane. 

University  of  Iowa  Studies  in  Psychology:  No.  VIII.  Edited 
by  Carl  E.  Seashore.  Psychological  Monographs :  Vol.  No.  31,  No.  1. 
Princeton.  Psychological  Review  Co.  1922.  382  pp. 

Nys,  D. :  La  Notion  d'espace.  Bruxelles:  Les  Editions  Robert 
Sand.  1922.  Pp.  448.  30  fr. 

Sainsbury,  Geoffrey:  Polarity.  London:  Favil  Press.  1922. 
48  pp.  3s  6d. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

A  joint  session  of  the  Mind  Association,  the  Aristotelian  Society 
and  the  British  Psychological  Society  was  held  in  Manchester  from 
July  14  to  18.  Most  of  the  papers  read  at  that  time  will  be  pub- 
lished in  the  October  issue  of  Mind. 

Professor  June  E.  Downey,  head  of  the  department  of  psychology 
at  the  University  of  Wyoming,  has  been  granted  leave  of  absence 
for  travel  and  study  during  the  academic  year  1922-23.  Miss  Louisa 
C.  Wagoner  will  be  acting  head  of  the  department  during  Professor 
Downey's  absence,  and  will  be  assisted  by  Mr.  Donald  A.  Laird  of 
the  University  of  Iowa. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  18  AUGUST  31,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  'PHILOSOPHY 


VALUE  AND  WORTH1 

HE  purpose  of  this  article  is  to  seek  common  ground  on  which 
-L  two  opposed  schools  of  value-philosophy  may  meet.  One 
school,  represented  recently  by  Perry,  Prall,  and  Pepper,  finds  the 
definition  of  intrinsic  value  in  the  affective-volitional  relation  of 
interest.  These  writers  conceive  value  to  have  a  psychological 
basis  in  feeling  and  to  designate  relations  between  an  individual 
and  objects  or  acts  liked  or  disliked.  The  other  school,  defended 
ably  in  America  by  Urban,  finds  value  asserted  in  a  unique  type 
of  judgment,  and  defines  it  as  a  category  of  being.  I  shall  not  dis- 
cuss a  third  view,  presented  by  Moore  and  Russell,  that  value  is  a 
quality,  for  I  agree  with  Urban 's  position  that  this  view  is  en- 
cumbered with  insuperable  difficulties.  Incidentally,  in  the  course 
of  the  article,  I  shall  reply  to  Mr.  Urban 's  generous  review  of  my 
book.2 

I 

The  exponents  of  a  relational  value-theory  maintain  that  value 
defined  as  a  relation  of  interest  is  a  sufficient  description  of  value 
wherever  it  occurs.  My  first  task  will  be  to  consider  Mr.  Urban 's 
objections  to  the  relational  theory.  I  shall  not,  however,  be  con- 
cerned to  defend  Sheldon's  ' ' ontological  definition"  of  value3  as 
"the  fulfilment  of  any  tendency  whatsoever."  Here  I  accept  Mr. 
Urban 's  criticism.  I  shall  hope  to  show,  however,  what  is  the  true 
bearing  of  the  latter 's  criticism  of  the  definition  that  is  psychologi- 
cal and  relational. 

Mr.  Urban  believes  that  a  relational  definition  of  value  is  circu- 

1  The  articles  most  frequently  cited  in  this  paper  are  those  by  Urban,  this 
JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIII,  pp.  449-465,  673-687;  Vol.  XIV,  pp.  309-327;  Vol.  XV, 
pp.  393-405.     I  also  cite,  from  the  same  JOURNAL,  those  by  Perry,  Vol.  XI,  pp. 
141-162,  and  Fisher,  Vol.  XIV,  pp.  570-582.     Also,  the  monograph  by  Prall, 
A  Study  in  the  Theory  of  Value,  Univ.  of  Cal.  Publications  in  Philosophy,  Vol. 
3,  No.  2,  1921,  and  my  book,  Values,  Immediate  and  Contributory,  and  Their 
Interrelation,  New  York  Univ.  Press,  1920. 

2  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIX,  pp.  53-55. 
s  Hid.,  Vol.  XIII,  pp.  453-455. 

477 


478  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

lar  in  character.  What  he  means,  I  think,  is  that  this  attempt  at 
definition  leaves  out  an  essential  (to  Mr.  Urban  the  essential) 
mark  of  value.  For  he  says*  that  "the  denial  that  value  can  ulti- 
mately be  defined  as  a  relation  does  not  mean  that  relational 
definitions  are  not  useful."  It  is  of  great  importance,  therefore, 
to  discover  just  what  is  omitted  in  a  relational  definition.  Mr. 
Urban 's  criticisms8  will  point  the  way. 

1.  "Why,  it  may  well  be  asked,  should  fulfilment  of  interest  be 
a  good?    Why  should  pleasure  confer  a  value T    In  all  such  defini- 
tions valuableness  is  already  assumed — as  an  intrinsic  quality  of 
pleasure  or  of  fulfilment,  as  the  case  may  be."     The  sequel  will 
show  that  I  recognize  that  all  included  under  the  word  value  can 
not  be  defined  as  affective-volitional  relations  of  interest.    But  it 
is  true  that  one  class  of  values,  sometimes  spoken  of  as  immediate, 
can  be  defined  adequately  in  such  terms.     I  may  like  or  dislike 
given  objects  or  acts  apart  from  any  reflection.    A  bright  color  or 
a  warm  breeze  may  arouse  in  me  a  thrill  of  pleasure.    To  defend  the 
application  of  the  term  value  to  such  experiences,  it  is  necessary 
only  to  indicate  that  it  has  a  clear  meaning  when  so  used.     Now 
when  I  speak  of  my  likings  and  dislikings  as  having  to  do  with 
value,  I  use  the  term  to  designate  relations  between  a  feeling  indi- 
vidual and  certain  objects  or  acts.    Value  is  not  assumed  to  be  "an 
intrinsic  quality   of   pleasure,"  for  the  relations  are  between  a 
pleased  or  displeased  individual  and  liked  or  disliked  objects  or 
acts.    "Interest"  may  be  used  in  almost  the  same  meaning,  although 
"interest"  frequently  emphasizes  the  first  term  and  "value"  the 
second  term  of  the  same  relation. 

2.  So  far  we  have  avoided  the  circularity  which  Mr.  Urban 
thinks  to  beset  a  relational  definition  of  all  value.     He  tells  us, 
however,  that  the  circularity  appears  in  another  way.    "The  value 
of  an  object  consists,  it  is  said,  in  its  satisfaction  of  desire,  or  more 
broadly,  fulfilment  of  interest.     But  it  is  always  possible  to  raise 
further  questions  which  show  conclusively  that  the  value  concept  is 
already  presupposed.     Is  the  interest  itself  worthy  of  being  satis- 
fied?   Is  the  object  worthy  of  being  of  interest?    In  other  words, 
the  fact  of  intrinsic  value  requires  us  to  find  the  essence  of  value 
in  something  other  than  this  type  of  relation." 

To  defend  the  adequacy  of  a  relational  definition  of  immediate 
values,  I  may  point  out  that  such  a  definition  is  adequate  because 
the  questions  raised  by  Mr.  Urban  are  not  a  part  of  the  experience. 
They  need  not  be  answered  because  they  are  not  asked.  My  liking 
for  a  hot  bath  may  have  no  reflective  basis.  Reflection  might  con- 

«/&id.,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  455,  footnote. 
•  Ibid.,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  453. 


VALUE  AND  WORTH  479 

vince  me  that  the  worth  of  a  hot  bath,  at  the  time  it  was  taken, 
was  entirely  negative.  Surely  we  are  not  compelled  to  analyze  our 
feelings  in  order  to  have  them,  and  I  can  see  no  objection  to  call- 
ing the  relations  that  come  into  being  when  things  are  liked  or  dis- 
liked, relations  of  immediate  value. 

It  is  quite  another  thing,  however,  to  maintain  that  all  that 
passes  under  the  name  of  value  may  be  defined  in  terms  of  affec- 
tive-volitional relations.  The  usual  criticism  of  the  position  that 
judgment  plays  an  essential  part  in  determining  some  values  is  to 
the  effect  that,  although  relations  of  interest  may  be  modified  by 
judgment,  such  judgment  does  not  alter  the  essential  nature  of 
value  which  is  still  to  be  described  in  terms  of  interest.  It  is  said 
that  although  I  may  begin  by  liking  jazz  and  end  by  liking  Brahms, 
value  first  and  last  is  my  interest  in  the  one  or  the  other.  As  Mr. 
Prall  says,6  ' '  Judgment,  while  it  may  be  instrumental  in  our  coming 
to  the  point  of  assuming  the  attitude  of  liking  toward  one  thing 
rather  than  another,  never  itself  constitutes  that  attitude.  The 
liking  is  all  we  have.  We  may  be  able  to  inquire  why  we  like ;  but 
when  we  do  thus  inquire,  we  only  analyze,  our  liking  into  its  re- 
spective parts  or  else  show  that  one  judgment  of  value  implies  the 
existence  of  another  value  than  the  one  judged." 

The  nature  of  these  contrasting  points  of  view  is  best  brought 
out  when  we  ask  how  each  is  related  to  conscious  activity.  On  the 
one  hand,  those  who  define  all  value  in  affective-volitional  terms 
assert  that  the  valuing  individual  is  related  to  the  objects  or  acts 
valued  through  feeling.  On  the  other  hand,  other  writers  main- 
tain that  this  type  of  definition  leaves  out  the  essential  element  of 
value,  and  they  find  this  essential  element  in  judgment.  Neverthe- 
less, those  who  hold  this  second  view  consider  that  feeling  plays  a 
part  in  the  value-experience,  so  that  it  may  be  said  that  they  de- 
scribe the  individual  as  both  knowing  and  feeling  in  the  experi- 
ence of  value.  The  first  view  is  that  of  Perry  and  Prall ;  the  second 
is  held  by  writers  of  such  different  viewpoints  as  Dewey,  Urban, 
Eickert,  and  Windelband.  The  latter  writers  have  no  psychological 
scruple  in  thus  blending  two  aspects  of  consciousness,  for  they  be- 
lieve that  the  value-experience  partakes  of  the  character  of  both. 
I  can  not  agree  with  this  viewpoint  for  reasons  which  I  shall  cite 
below.  My  suggested  solution  of  the  problem  will  lie  in  the  direc- 
tion of  maintaining  that  there  are  two  broad  types  of  values,  one 
of  which  may  be  defined  adequately  as  affective-volitional  rela- 
tions of  interest,  the  other  as  worth  which  lies  wholly  within  the 
realm  of  cognition. 

«  Prall,  op.  cit.,  p.  267. 


480  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

II 

Mr.  Urban  feels  that  the  affective-volitional  definition  leaves 
out  the  element  of  the  worth  of  the  feeling.  Three  possible  view- 
points may  be  taken  as  to  the  position  that  worth  occupies  in  con- 
scious experience.  (1)  Worth  may  still  lie  within  feeling  when  it 
is  not  determined  wholly  by  feeling-relations.  In  other  words,  there 
may  be  some  aspect  of  being,  independent  of  the  individual,  which 
is  of  the  nature  of  feeling,  or  at  least  near  enough  like  feeling  to  be 
felt.  To  describe  the  relation  of  the  valuing  individual  to  such  an 
"over-individual"  worth-determinant,  we  should  have  to  invent  a 
term  in  the  language  of  feeling  to  correspond  with  "apprehension" 
in  the  language  of  cognition.  (2)  Worth  may  be  apprehended  in 
the  value- judgment  which  is  the  cognitive  aspect  of  a  whole  ex- 
perience of  value  in  which  cognition  and  feeling  are  blended.  (3) 
Worth  may  be  cognized  only,  and  this  worth-experience  may  be 
quite  distinct  from  the  feeling-relation  of  value  between  the  indi- 
vidual who  has  the  worth-experience  and  the  object  esteemed.  The 
desirability  of  making  a  distinction  between  value  and  worth  was 
first  suggested  to  me  in  a  letter  from  Miss  Mary  Case.  Mr.  Pepper 's 
paper,  "Primitive  and  Standard  Value,"  recently  read  before  the 
American  Philosophical  Association  (1922),  also  led  me  to  think 
of  the  implications  of  such  a  distinction. 

I  shall  first  consider  the  position  that  worth  is  in  some  way  ex- 
perienced through  feeling.  To  describe  this  view  adequately  re- 
quires delicate  handling.  It  is  substantially  that  of  Mr.  Fisher, 
although  I  am  not  always  clear  as  to  his  full  meaning.  Both  he 
and  Mr.  Urban  believe  that  value  (Urban)  or  an  object's  value 
(Fisher)  is  apprehended  in  the  value- judgment.  But  Mr.  Fisher 
denies7  that  value  itself  is  apprehended  by  the  cognitive  aspect  of 
consciousness,  although  he  holds  that  the  complex  "  value-of -an- 
object"  may  thus  be  apprehended.  I  think  that  he  means  that  a 
cognitive  element  enters  our  experience  of  value  when  we  attribute 
worth  to  a  particular  object.  This  judgment  of  worth  of  an  ob- 
ject is  to  be  distinguished  from  worth  itself  which  is  "apprehended" 
through  feeling.  I  caji  not  help  feeling  that  much  remains  unsaid 
by  Mr.  Fisher  regarding  the  relation  of  the  worth  apprehended  by 
feeling  to  the  worth  attributed  to  objects  in  the  value-judgment. 
But  I  am  not  concerned  here  with  enlarging  on  this  question;  the 
more  fundamental  question  is  whether  worth  may  lie  wholly  within 
the  sphere  of  feeling. 

Mr.  Fisher  believes  that  we  are  unable  to  have  knowledge  of 
worth  because  worth  is  apprehended  through  some  form  of  feeling. 

T  Thia  JOUBNAL,  VoL  XIV,  p.  578. 


VALUE  AND  WORTH  481 

He  accepts,  therefore,  one  horn  of  Perry's  dilemma8  ("The  attitude 
of  interest  either  constitutes  values  or  it  cognizes  them"),  and  very 
logically  denies  that  worth  can  be  cognized  at  all.  Knowledge 
about  worth  we  may  have,  as  we  have  knowledge  about  feeling,  but 
we  can  no  more  cognize  worth  itself  than  we  can  inspect  feeling 
through  a  microscope.  I  can  not  but  feel  that  Urban  impales 
Fisher  on  the  wrong  horn  of  the  dilemma.  Because  he  fails  to  see 
the  importance  of  Fisher's  distinction  between  value  and  an  ob- 
ject's value,  and  because  Fisher  uses  the  term  "apprehension"  of 
worth  and  speaks  as  if  feeling  "merely  furnishes  the  requisite 
sensibility"  for  such  apprehension,  Urban  takes  it  for  granted  that 
he  believes  that  worth  may  be  cognized.  This  misapprehension 
arises  partly  through  lack  of  a  proper  nomenclature,  and  partly 
through  the  lack  of  sufficient  explanation  by  Fisher  as  to  how  ob- 
jects get  a  value  that  lies  within  the  realm  of  feeling.  On  the  other 
hand,  if  he  holds  that  worth  is  apprehended  by  feeling,  he  can 
suitably  deny  that  worth  itself  can  be  cognized. 

"What  is  the  bearing  of  a  theory  that  worth  is  apprehended  by 
feeling?  The  answer  to  this  question  would  be  contained  in  a 
discipline  concerned  with  feeling  much  as  epistemology  is  con- 
cerned with  cognition.  Is  there  objective  worth  which  is  affirmed 
(for  want  of  a  better  term)  by  feeling,  and  which  is  an  attribute 
(not  a  quality)  of  the  objects  of  certain  feeling-relations,  but 
which  lies  outside  that  portion  of  given  experience  which  is  open 
to  cognition?  Empirical  evidence  for  such  a  theory  might  be 
sought  among  primitive  esthetic  satisfactions  produced  by  colors, 
harmonies,  etc.,  if  some  of  these  might  be  found  to  be  without 
adequate  psycho-physical  explanation.  In  other  words,  it  might  be 
proved  that  we  face  a  kind  of  brute  reality  in  the  worth-experience 
which  can  be  explained  only  on  the  assumption  that  there  is  a 
category  of  feeling  within  the  realm  of  being  that  is  just  as  un- 
alterable as  the  reality  underlying  the  objects  of  cognition. 

If  such  a  theory  were  proved  a  fact,  beauty  would  be  shown  to 
be  independent  of  its  apprehension;  it  would  transcend  relations 
of  interest;  and  I  doubt  the  wisdom  of  applying  the  term  "value" 
to  it  at  all.  The  evidence  bearing  on  the  theory  is  of  such  great 
complexity  that  after  several  years  of  reflection  I  am  yet  unable 
to  form  an  opinion.  I  should  welcome  light  from  Mr.  Fisher.  If, 
however,  it  should  be  proved  that  worth  of  a  certain  kind  is  ap- 
prehended through  feeling,  such  worth  would  be  entirely  distinct 
from  the  cognitive  worth  that  I  am  about  to  discuss. 

Having  considered  Mr.  Fisher's  position,   I  now  turn  to  the 

s  Ibid.,  Vol.  XI,  p.  152. 


482  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

second  and  third  possible  standpoints  regarding  attribution  of 
worth.  Worth,  as  Mr.  Urban  thinks,  may  be  attributed  to  an  object 
in  a  value-judgment,  the  whole  experience  being  of  both  a  cogni- 
tive and  an  affective  character.  Mr.  Urban 's  treatment  of  the 
value- judgment  leaves  no  room  for  doubt  that  this  is  the  meaning 
intended.  He  claims  that  we  know  value  by  affirmation  in  judg- 
ment,6 and  also  that  in  making  a  value-judgment  we  are  governed 
by  an  a  priori  law  which  works  in  us  as  "on  essential  form  of  inter- 
est and  volition  as  such."10  I  am  not  at  the  moment  concerned 
with  his  theory  that  value  is  a  category  of  reality  apart  from  our  ex- 
perience, but  solely  with  the  one  point  that  whenever  we  experience 
value,  we  are  said  to  do  so  through  both  cognition  and  feeling.  An 
experience  of  worth,  under  this  view,  must  be  referred  to  conscious 
activity  as  a  whole  if  it  is  to  be  given  a  psychological  description. 

Against  this  view,  I  hold  that  value  and  worth,  when  analyzed, 
prove  to  be  distinct,  and  that  the  term  "intrinsic  worth"  has  been 
applied  ambiguously  to  designate  now  the  one,  now  the  other. 
First,  I  shall  give  instances  of  this  confusion;  secondly,  I  shall 
proceed  to  develop  the  view  that  the  two  types  of  intrinsic  worth 
have  distinct  psychological  bases,  a  task  that  will  involve  a  criti- 
cism of  Mr.  Urban 's  theory  of  value-judgments. 

1.  I  find  a  common  assumption  underlying  the  radically  differ- 
ent views  of  Perry,  Urban,  Prall,  and  Dewey.  It  is  that  the  in- 
trinsic values  defined  as  affective-volitional  relations  of  interest  are 
the  same  sort  of  entities  as  the  intrinsic  values  which  appear  when 
we  ask  questions  as  to  whether  the  worths  are  justified.  Perry  ana- 
lyzes the  complex  state  of  mind  when  one  judges  a  value  into  judg- 
ments of  fact  plus  feeling  for  the  object  judged.11  This  feeling, 
for  him,  constitutes  the  value.  Perry's  position,  therefore,  is  that 
intrinsic  value,  whether  it  be  reflective  or  immediate,  is  equally 
constituted  by  feeling  for  an  object,  i.e.,  that  intrinsic  value  is 
always  affective-volitional. 

Prall12  has  shown  recently  in  a  forceful  way  that  a  judgment  of 
contributory  value  such  as  "The  pen  is  good  for  writing"  implies 
the  intrinsic  worths  of  the  "higher  values"  of  truth,  goodness,  and 
contemplation.  But  Mr.  Frail's  thesis  is  that  of  "the  identical  na- 
ture of  value  as  it  appears  in  all  cases  of  valuing."18  Prall  and 
Perry  agree  that  value  is  constituted  by  interest,  and  that  judg- 
ments of  value  do  not  affect  the  basic  nature  of  value  itself  or  bring 

•  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  463. 

10  Ibid.,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  677. 

"  Ibid.,  VoL  XI,  pp.  161-162. 

"  Prall,  op.  cit.,  p.  266. 

»«/&«.,  p.  254. 


VALUE  AND  WORTH  483 

to  light  any  new  class  of  values.  Urban,  as  we  have  seen,  assumes 
the  identity  of  the  value  defined  as  relational  with  the  worth  that 
appears  after  questions  are  asked  as  to  its  justification.  Further- 
more, in  his  later  theory  of  value,  he  attempts  to  identify  in  kind 
all  cases  of  intrinsic  value  by  claiming  that  value  is  apprehended 
in  a  special  kind  of  judgment,  while  maintaining  at  the  same  time 
that  value  is  "an  essential  form  of  interest  and  volition  as  such."  14 
Finally,  Dewey,15  while  recognizing  the  distinctness  of  many  classes 
of  values,  speaks  of  certain  judgments  plus  subsequent  acts  bring- 
ing into  existence  new  intrinsic  values.  He  thus  regards  affective- 
volitional  values  as  of  the  same  nature  as  the  new  intrinsic  values 
which  appear  in  consequence  of  judgment,  in  so  far  as  interest  is 
concerned.  The  new  values  differ,  of  course,  in  their  cognitional 
aspect.  Dewey  and  Urban,  therefore,  blend  feeling  and  cognition 
in  their  descriptions  of  the  values  of  appreciation  in  different  ways. 
They  make  feeling  an  essential  element  of  the  worths  affirmed  in 
value-judgments,  and  neither  of  them  would  agree  that  the  intrin- 
sic worth  affirmed  in  judgment  does  not  contain  the  same  element 
of  feeling  that  creates  simple,  immediate  values. 

I  submit  that  each  of  these  writers  fails  adequately  to  analyze 
intrinsic  value.  I  believe  that  much  diversity  of  opinion  will  dis- 
appear when  it  is  recognized  that  this  term  has  been  applied  indis- 
criminately to  value  and  worth.  Although  Miss  Case  first  suggested 
the  desirability  of  the  distinction,  I  can  not  say,  of  course,  that 
either  she  or  Mr.  Pepper,  who  recalled  it  to  mind,  would  accept  my 
development  of  it. 

2.  Let  me  begin  with  a  word  of  caution.  I  do  not  assert  that 
feeling  and  cognition  may  be  separated  in  existence.  Elsewhere10 
I  have  amplified  this  statement.  While  describing  conscious  activ- 
ity as  related  to  environment  in  two  ways,  I  have  not  departed 
from  the  accepted  psychological  fact  that  feeling  and  cognition 
never  occur  in  isolation.  I  do  claim,  however,  that  the  affective  and 
cognitive  elements  are  always  distinct  upon  introspective  analysis, 
and  that  we  can  say  of  no  conscious  state  that  it  contains  a  blend  of 
feeling  and  cognition  that  defies  analysis  into  two  distinct  aspects.17 
The  purpose  of  this  article  is  to  prove  that  intrinsic  value  never 
properly  designates  the  relation  of  objects  to  both  aspects  of  con- 
scious activity  at  once,  but  that  there  are  two  distinct  types  of  in- 

i*  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  677. 
15  In  a  paper  now  in  press. 

I8 ' '  The  Coordinate  Character  of  Feeling  and  Cognition, ' '  this  JOURNAL, 
Vol.  XVIII,  pp.  288-295. 

17  Values,  Immediate  and  Contributory,  and  Their  Interrelation,  pp.  94-104. 


484  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

trinsic  worth,  concerned  with  the  relation  of  objects  to  feeling  and 
cognition,  respectively. 

(1)  Interest  and  Worth. — Consideration  of  an  objection  to  the 
distinction  between  immediate  value  and  cognitive  worth  may 
serve  as  our  starting-point.  Perry  and  Prall  claim  that  however 
modified  our  ascription  of  worth  may  become  in  consequence  of 
judgment,  the  constitutive  factor  of  both  immediate  value  and  cogni- 
tive worth  always  remains  the  element  of  interest.  My  enjoyment  of 
a  Bach  fugue,  however  increased  by  study  of  its  counterpoint,  must 
in  the  end  be  referred  to  my  liking  for  it,  and  this  enjoyment  is  of 
the  same  nature  as  that  which  I  experience  when  I  taste  a  savory 
morsel.  I  reply  that  this  statement,  if  adduced  as  an  argument  for 
the  identity  of  the  factor  that  constitutes  immediate  value  with  that 
which  constitutes  intrinsic  worth,  is  a  non  sequitur.  Since  feeling 
is  never  divorced  from  cognition  in  conscious  experience,  it  goes 
without  saying  that  there  are  affective  value-relations  present  in 
every  moment  of  conscious  activity.  This  fact,  however,  does  not 
take  into  account  the  additional  element  of  worth  that  may  appear 
upon  the  reflection.  Perry  and  Prall  uncritically  identify  affective 
interest  with  interest  that  is  wholly  cognitive.  To  separate  the  two 
kinds  of  interest,  it  is  only  necessary  to  reflect  that  immediate  value 
may  be  positive  while  at  the  same  time  cognitive  worth  is  negative, 
and  vice  versa.  I  may  continue  to  like  a  certain  picture  that  my 
newly  acquired  esthetic  taste  condemns.  I  may  heartily  dislike  music 
that  I  know  and  recognize  to  be  "good."  The  confusion  of  these 
writers  is  due  to  an  uncritical  identification  of  two  distinct  types  of 
interest. 

In  the  moral  and  esthetic  spheres,  recognition  of  worth  and  lik- 
ing for  the  object  or  act  esteemed  have  too  often  been  identified  by 
philosophers.  In  the  case  of  ethics,  the  moral  conflict  that  often 
occurs  between  what  I  like  and  what  I  recognize  to  be  best  would 
seem  to  be  sufficient  empirical  evidence  to  destroy  this  notion. 
Knowledge  and  virtue  and  pleasure  would  go  hand  in  hand  if  an 
ideal  of  harmonious  functioning  were  stipulated  and  attained,  but 
practically  I  may  reflect  with  little  pleasure  upon  an  act  to  which 
I  ascribe  great  moral  worth.  Again,  Dewey's  discussion  of  "valua- 
tions" that  are  not  final  until  I  have  performed  an  act  in  conse- 
quence of  a  preliminary  judgment  goes  to  prove  that  not  only 
reflection,  but  also  practical  activities  may  contribute  to  the  modifi- 
cation of  worths  previously  ascribed,  but  it  does  not  imply  that  my 
liking  has  changed  gradually  in  the  process  in  the  positive  direction. 
That  may  or  may  not  be  the  case.  To  claim  that  the  recognition  of 
moral  worth  is  the  same  as  the  felt  value  of  moral  worth  is  to  dis- 


VALUE  AND  WORTH  485 

regard  the  experience  of  moral  conflict.  And  if  it  is  true  that 
certain  ethical  systems  base  their  standards  of  moral  worth  en  felt 
pleasure,  it  is  also  true  that  other  systems  are  equally  well  able  to 
entertain  the  notion  of  moral  worth  that  becomes  pleasurable  only 
after  the  natural  affections  have  been  suppressed  in  its  favor. 

In  his  definition  of  the  esthetic  experience,  Mr.  Prall  gives  an  un- 
conscious illustration  of  this  distinction.  He  says,18  "We  may  value 
for  itself  the  good  act  which  expresses  the  good  will ;  but  the  more 
completely  we  value  it  in  itself,  the  more  completely  do  we  simply 
dwell  upon  it  in  contemplation,  give  ourselves  over  to  it  as  total  ob- 
ject, lose  ourselves  in  it.  And  what  we  are  interested  in  in  this  com- 
plete way,  in  pure  contemplation,  in  disinterested  attentiveness,  is 
what  we  call  the  esthetically  valuable"  (italics  mine).  It  may  be 
said  fairly  that  an  interest  which  may  be  described  as  ' '  disinterested 
attentiveness"  is  quite  other  than  the  interest  of  which  we  speak 
when  we  discuss  affective  relations. 

(2)  Value-Judgments  and  Worth. — The  distinction  between  im- 
mediate value  and  worth  rests  on  empirical  grounds.  But  we  have 
still  to  show  that  the  experience  of  worth  does  not  in  itself  contain 
an  element  of  feeling.  Undoubtedly,  there  are  affective  elements 
present  at  the  time  one  has  the  worth-experience.  The  question  is 
whether  the  worth-experience  itself  is  partly  constituted  by  feeling, 
or  whether  it  is  wholly  cognitive  (in  the  same  sense  as  we  say  that 
to  know  is  not  to  feel,  although  we  must  do  both  at  each  conscious 
moment).  Any  writer  who  confuses  affective  with  cognitive  inter- 
est is  likely  to  define  the  experience  of  worth  partly  in  terms  of 
feeling,  partly  in  those  of  cognition,  if,  indeed,  he  does  not  restrict 
both  value  and  worth  to  the  affective  factor.  Dewey  and  Urban 
both  describe  classes  of  worths  that  are  neither  wholly  cognitive  nor 
wholly  affective.  I  shall  content  myself  here  with  a  criticism  of 
Mr.  Urbaji's  position,  that  being  the  more  extreme. 

Value-judgments  may  or  may  not  imply  the  recognition  of  stand- 
ards of  worth.  One  class  of  value- judgments  contains  no  implica- 
tion of  worth.  "I  like  smoking"  may  serve  merely  to  bring  to 
conscious  attention  a  fact  of  affective  value.  No  question  need  be 
raised  as  to  the  worth  of  smoking,  because  none  is  raised.  But  once 
that  I  do  raise  such  a  question,  it  becomes  of  importance  to  investi- 
gate the  nature  of  the  worth  that  is  affirmed.  If  Mr.  Urban  would 
accept  this  standpoint,  he  might  contribute  much  toward  our  knowl- 
edge of  worth-affirmation.  He  would  argue,  I  believe,  that  the  ob- 
jective nature  of  worth  lies  in  the  form  rather  than  in  the  matter  of 
affirmation.  Value-judgments  do  not  guarantee  any  particular 

"  Prall,  p.  266. 


486  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

worths,  such  as  happiness  or  goodness,  but  they  all  have  a  common 
form,  and  this  form  is  of  the  nature  of  a  category  of  judgment.  But 
let  us  see  how  Mr.  Urban  leads  up  to  his  theory  of  value-judgment. 

After  rejecting  definitions  of  value  in  relational  or  qualitative 
terms,  Mr.  Urban  investigated  the  possibilities  latent  in  the  substan- 
tival form  of  expression  of  values.  Often  we  say,  "This  is  a  worth." 
One  who  still  clings  to  the  relational  form  of  definition  can  readily 
explain  this  usage  by  calling  attention  to  the  fact  that  we  frequently 
use  single  words  to  designate  relations.  "James  shows  backwardness 
in  his  studies"  means  that  James  has  other  boys  ahead  of  him.  But 
Mr.  Urban  believes  that  it  is  not  only  possible  to  use  value  in  sub- 
stantival fashion,  but  that  the  notion  of  value  can  be  rendered  ade- 
quately only  in  the  proposition  "that  A  ought  to  be  on  its  own 
account,"  and  he  concludes  that  value  is  an  objective,  so  far  as  it  is 
amenable  to  expression  in  language.19  More  explicitly,  the  value- 
judgment  involves,  in  addition  to  the  judgment  itself,  "on  essential 
form  of  interest  and  volition  as  such."  20 

Limitation  of  space  prohibits  me  from  entering  in  detail  into  the 
minuticB  of  the  controversy  between  Urban  and  Fisher  over  the  pos- 
sibility of  conceiving  value  as  an  objective  in  Meinong's  sense.  For- 
tunately for  my  purpose,  such  discussion  will  not  be  required.  It 
will  be  sufficient  to  show  that  the  alleged  typical  value- judgment 
imports  a  special  connotation  into  the  term  "intrinsic  worth,"  and 
then  to  show  that  any  expression  of  worth  in  judgment  conforms  to 
a  type  that  I  shall  make  clear. 

Mr.  Urban,  as  against  Fisher,  holds  that  oughtness  in  the  value- 
judgment  is  quite  distinct  from  obligation,  and  that  the  latter  is  a 
special  case  of  the  former.  In  his  reply  to  Fisher,21  he  refers  to  his 
previous  argument.22  As  I  think,  he  made  two  points.  (1)  "Nor 
have  I  space  to  rehearse  how,  after  showing  that  intrinsic  value  is 
ultimately  indefinable  in  terms  either  of  quality  or  relation,  it  can 
be  finally  stated  only  as  equivalent  to  'ought  to  be.'  My  critic  does 
not  even  refer  to  these  arguments,  much  less  meet  them."  (2)  "Of 
many  things  we  can  say  that  they  ought  to  be,  when  it  would  be 
wholly  absurd  to  think  that  this  notion  involved  a  command  to  any 
person  or  group  of  persons. ' '  Now  since  I  have  admitted  that  worth 
involves  something  more  than  affective-relational  value,  and  since 
I  believe  that  an  adequate  definition  of  worth  can  be  attained  in  some 
other  way  than  through  the  "typical  value- judgment,"  the  first  point 
may  await  the  sequel.  But  I  would  join  with  Fisher  in  denying  that 

»»This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  462. 
*>  Ibid.,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  677. 
»i  Ibid.,  Vol.  XV,  p.  398. 
» Ibid.,  Vol.  XIH,  p.  462. 


VALUE  AND  WORTH  487 

ought  is  ever  used  (except  by  Mr.  Urban)  without  the  notion  of 
obligation.  Mr.  Urban  says,28  "Is  it  not  sufficient  to  recall  again  that 
we  often  say  that  things  ought  to  have  been  otherwise  when  we 
have  not  the  slightest  intention  of  ascribing  obligation  to  them?" 
This,  however,  was  hardly  Fisher's  point.  The  latter  argued  that 
ought  involves  always  the  notion  of  obligation  of  a  person  or  group 
of  persons,  not  of  the  things  concerned.  One  wishes  that  Mr.  Urban 
had  given  concrete  examples.  He  shows 24  correctly  that  Perry 's 
criticism  does  not  touch  the  point  because  his  illustrations  are  ill- 
chosen.  Perhaps  the  following  examples  will  suffice :  ' '  The  Lusitania 
ought  not  to  have  been  sunk. ' '  Here  it  is  stated  that  an  event  should 
not  have  taken  place.  Is  there  not,  however,  in  the  mind  of  the 
speaker  the  notion  of  moral  obligation  unfulfiled  by  those  who  were 
responsible  for  sinking  the  ship?  "John  ought  to  have  been  happy, 
for  he  was  a  good  man,  but  circumstances  were  against  him. ' '  Does 
not  this  imply  that  some  beneficent  Power  should  have  arranged 
circumstances  otherwise?  I  can  not  protest  too  strongly  against  the 
practise  of  making  the  judgment  of  moral  worth  typical  of  all  in- 
trinsic worth. 

In  his  review  25  of  my  book,  Mr.  Urban  says  that  I  deny  that 
there  are  judgments  of  intrinsic  value.  I  presume  that  "of"  is 
here  the  sign  of  an  objective  genitive,  and  that  he  means  that  I  deny 
that  judgment  is  the  means  whereby  intrinsic  values  are  apprehended. 
From  what  I  have  said,  it  will  be  obvious  that  I  am  now  engaged  in 
proving  that  worth,  as  distinguished  from  immediate  value,  is  brought 
into  being  by  reflection,  and  that  intrinsic  worth  therefore  is  affirmed 
in  judgment.  My  book  did  not  treat  of  worth-judgments  from  this 
point  of  view.  To  be  clear,  let  me  mention  briefly  some  of  the  values 
that  are  associated  with  a  judgment  of  intrinsic  worth. 

' '  Goodness  is  valuable  in  itself. ' '  First,  there  is  the  contributory 
value  of  the  act  of  judgment,  this  particular  judgment,  like  all  judg- 
ments, being  a  means  to  the  end  of  self-expression.  Secondly,  there 
is  the  value  of  the  content  of  the  judgment  for  the  one  who  judges, 
which  varies  according  to  the  range  of  application  to  practical  activi- 
ties— here  the  range  is  wide.  This  is  also  contributory  in  character. 
Thirdly,  there  is  the  value  that  springs  from  my  liking  or  disliking 
the  object  judged  (goodness).  This  is  value  of  the  immediate  type. 
With  these  values  I  was  chiefly  concerned  in  the  constructive  portion 
of  my  book.  Finally,  there  is  the  affirmation  of  the  worth  of  goodness, 
which  I  should  rate  as  a  type  distinct  from  either  immediate  or  con- 

23  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XV,  p.  398. 

2*  Ibid.,  Vol.  XV,  p.  401. 

25 /bid.,  Vol.  XIX,  pp.  53-55. 


488  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

tributary  value,  but  which  is  more  nearly  allied  formally  to  con- 
tributory value  than  to  immediate. 

Mr.  Urban  believes  that  I  use  the  term  "contributory  value" 
equivocally,  now  as  signifying  a  means  to  an  end,  now  in  the  mean- 
ing of  "adding  to  the  functioning  of  conscious  activity."  I  have 
guarded,  however,  against  such  an  equivocation.  The  sense  in  which 
all  judgments  are  contributory  because  they  add  to  the  functioning 
of  conscious  activity  is,  as  Mr.  Urban  fails  to  note,  from  the  stand- 
point of  an  observer.  Now  while  the  judging  individual  is  not  him- 
self making  a  judgment  about  intrinsic  worth  as  additive  to  con- 
scious activity,  an  observer  who  looks  upon  the  activity  of  the  indi- 
vidual must  regard  all  judgments,  nay,  every  instance  of  conscious 
functioning,  as  a  means  to  the  end  of  modifying  in  some  way  the 
contact  of  the  individual  with  his  environment. 

Here  I  wish  to  go  further  than  I  did  in  my  book  and  maintain 
that  judgments  of  worth  fall  into  a  form  common  to  them  and  to  all 
contributory  values.  And  I  shall  take  care  to  exhibit  this  fact  in  its 
naturalness,  rather  than  to  "force"  these  judgments,  "in  pragmatic 
fashion,  into  the  instrumental  mold." 

To  begin  with,  worth  is  not  fully  expressed  in  such  a  judgment 
as  "A  has  worth."  We  ask  what  kind  of  worth  it  has.  Is  it  a  means 
to  an  end  T  Then  it  will  be  of  contributory  value.  Or  is  it  worthy  in 
itself  T  Then  it  has  intrinsic  worth.  Observe  that  Mr.  Urban 's  typ- 
ical value-judgment  contains  the  words  "on  its  own  account."  Some 
such  expression  is  needed  to  clear  the  meaning,  to  distinguish  worth 
that  is  contributory  from  worth  that  is  intrinsic.  Now  I  find  a  com- 
mon structure  and  a  common  element  in  judgments  of  both  contribu- 
tory and  intrinsic  worth.  The  common  element  is  a  point  of  refer- 
ence of  the  worth  to  some  object  or  act.  In  the  case  of  contributory 
value,  A  is  worthy  as  a  means  to  an  end.  In  the  case  of  intrinsic 
worth,  however,  the  worth  of  A  is  referred  back  to  itself,  and  descrip- 
tion of  the  worth  is  incomplete  until  this  backward  reference  is  made. 
On  the  basis  of  these  considerations,  it  would  be  allowable  to  treat 
all  worth  as  referential,  and  to  discuss  two  types  of  worth,  of  which 
the  differentia  is  the  point  of  reference. 

Nor  only  do  all  worth-judgments  exhibit  a  common  referential 
characteristic;  they  also  exhibit  a  common  structure.  I  find  this 
structure  most  conveniently  described  as  that  of  a  triadic  relation. 
In  this  way  it  may  be  distinguished  from  the  structure  of  immediate 
value  which  is  dyadic — the  terms  here  being  individual  and  object 
or  act.  A  worth-relation  has  three  terms:  individual,  the  object  or 
act  judged,  and  the  object  or  act  to  which  the  judged  object  is 
referred. 


MIND  IN  THE  MECHANICAL  ORDER  489 

From  these  considerations,  based  upon  empirical  evidence  and  an 
analysis  of  judgments  of  worth,  I  hope  to  have  established  (1)  the 
distinct  natures  of  immediate  value  and  intrinsic  worth,  (2)  the 
psychological  basis  in  cognition  of  all  kinds  of  worth,  (3)  the  ade- 
quacy of  relational  definitions  of  both  value  and  worth,  one  as 
dyadic,  the  other  as  triadic,  (4)  the  common  form  of  judgments  of 
contributory  value  and  judgments  of  intrinsic  worth. 

I  have  not  space  to  discuss  in  detail  Mr.  Urban 's  interesting 
metaphysical  speculations.  I  would,  however,  instance  a  most  un- 
warranted assumption  that  he  makes.  He  says,26  "That  a  specific 
object  has  positive  or  negative  value,  as  the  case  may  be,  and  why  it 
has  value,  are  matters  of  interest,  feeling,  and  desire;  but  that  it 
must  fall  somewhere  in  the  scale  of  value,  this  is  an  essential  form  of 
interest  and  volition  as  such,  logically  prior  to  any  experience  of 
desire  or  feeling.  Over  against  the  world  of  mere  objects  as  such 
are  the  categories  of  being  and  value,  all-inclusive  forms  of  the 
world."  Why  "of  the  world"?  Surely,  only  on  an  assumption  of 
the  truth  of  idealism.  As  an  epistemological  dualist  I  am  con- 
strained to  remark  that  the  category  of  value  may  only  be  inferred  to 
be  a  category  or  form  of  the  judgment-process;  whether  or  not  it 
extends  beyond  the  given  to  the  world  will  depend  upon  what  kind 
of  a  world  we  have. 

I  believe  that  I  have  replied  to  most  of  Mr.  Urban 's  criticisms. 
It  is  strange,  however,  to  read  that  I  "describe  myself  as  a  Pragma- 
tist  with  certain  reservations."  The  agreement  with  pragmatism 
expressed  in  my  book  was  restricted  to  one  point  of  method.  I  men- 
tion this  more  personal  matter  because  it  affords  an  instance  of  the 
danger  of  affixing  labels  to  philosophical  standpoints  which  recognize 
that  truth  is  not  the  prerogative  of  any  single  sect  of  philosophical 
opinion. 

MAURICE  PICARD. 

BARNAKD  COLLEGE. 

MIND  IN  THE  MECHANICAL  ORDER 

T~  F  I  have  properly  understood  the  intent  of  the  article  on  ' '  Prag- 
•*•  matism  and  the  New  Materialism, ' ' x  Professor  Lovejoy  's 
criticism  is  directed  not  altogether  against  pragmatism  and  be- 
haviorism as  such,  but  rather  in  part  at  least  against  certain  phil- 
osophies which,  having  on  some  points  misunderstood  the  meaning 
of  these  movements,  have  yet  taken  on  their  insignia  and  ended  by 
deforming  the  spirit  of  their  thought.  While  it  is  not  always  easy 

ze  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  677. 
i  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIX,  no.  1. 


I.)!)  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

to  distinguish  between  the  behaviorists  and  those  who  only  call 
themselves  such,  I  have  unavoidably  the  impression  that  a  part  at 
least  of  the  polemic  is  directed  against  some  of  the  neo-realists,  who 
have  "joined  forces"  with  behaviorism,  rather  than  against  the 
original  representatives  of  the  school  itself.2 

When  Mr.  Lovejoy  proposes  to  the  pragmatist,  or  to  any  one 
else,  his  five  conundrums  about  the  place  of  mind  in  the  mechanical 
or  "physical"  order,  one  has  a  right  to  know  what  he  means  by 
his  terms.  "Physical"  means,  he  says,  "occupying  a  position  in 
objective  space  and  existing  as  a  part  of  the  sum  of  masses  and 
forces  dealt  with  by  physical  science."  This  he  quotes.  Does  he 
agree  to  the  meaning  or  does  he  even  think  that  the  statement  is 
clear?  Does  any  one  suppose  that  the  physical  order  is  independ- 
ent of  mind!  Or  does  not  its  nature  change  as  the  mind  succeeds 
more  and  more  in  imposing  it  upon  the  world?  For  the  mechani- 
cal order  may  not  be  absolute;  it  may  be  slowly  evolved  by  means 
of  the  twin  factors  of  experience  and  reflection.  Let  it  not  be  for- 
gotten that  mass  and  space  and  time  change  their  meaning  as  ex- 
perience is  enriched  and  reinterpreted;  that  the  mechanical  order 
of  nature  is  not  the  absolute  and  static  system  it  was  taken  to  be, 
when  it  achieved  its  first  successes.  Does  any  one  suppose  that 
throughout  the  age-long  effort  to  describe  nature  in  mechanical 
terms  those  terms  will  retain  their  original  and  primitive  meaning? 
Will  mass  forever  and  infallibly  suggest  the  name  of  Galileo  or 
Democritus,  or  space  the  name  of  Euclid,  or  time  the  name  of  Kant 
or  Newton?  To  a  student  of  the  history  of  scientific  conceptions 
nothing  could  appear  more  improbable,  nothing  could  appear  more 
unnatural  than  this. 

The  difficulty  of  a  number  of  gentlemen  who  call  themselves 
"realists"  consists,  or  so  it  seems  to  me,  in  the  assumption  of  an 
absolute  mechanical  order,  which,  if  not  grasped,  is  at  any  rate 
grasped  approximately.  Approximately  to  what?  Why,  to  that 
absolute  which  he  assumes,  but  about  which  he  remains  inarticulate. 
Let  him  define  what  he  means  by  the  real  order  of  nature  and  I 
shall  understand  what  is  meant  by  a  knowledge  which  approximates 
to  it.  But  define  it  in  his  "sense"  he  can  not. 

Choose  as  an  illustration,  if  you  will,  the  simplest  experiment 
to  be  found  in  the  laboratory  list.  Suppose  that  your  problem  is 
to  find  the  distance  between  two  scratches  on  a  piece  of  glass.  He 
will  say  perhaps  that  there  is  an  observed  or  approximate  length 

2  The  thesis  that  mind  is  describable  in  terms  of  behavior  was  first  elabo- 
rate! by  Professor  Singer  in  a  series  of  articles  in  this  JOURNAL;  1911,  p.  180; 
1912,  pp.  15  and  206;  1914,  p.  645;  1917,  p.  337.  These  papers  easily  remain 
the  best  formulation  of  the  beharioristic  standpoint. 


MIND  IN  THE  MECHANICAL  ORDER  491 

and  there  is  also  an  absolute  length,  which,  because  of  the  error  at- 
tached to  every  observation,  remains  forever  unobserved.  The  real 
length  is  the  limit  of  a  series  of  approximations,  a  Grenzbegriff. 
You  focus  the  cross  wires  of  your  micrometer  microscope  upon  the 
object  and  you  take  in  succession  a  number  of  readings.  These 
readings  differ  inter  se.  They  can  not  all  be  "true."  It  is  mean- 
ingless to  speak  of  any  one  as  ' '  correct. ' '  The  arithmetical  mean  is 
the  "best"  approximation.  Approximation  to  what?  Why,  to  the 
Grenzbegriff. 

Now  I  can  understand  what  it  means  to  speak  of  a  limit  to  the 
series, 


because  each  term  is  formed  from  its  predecessor  according  to  a 
definite  law.  But  what  does  it  mean  to  speak  of  the  limit  of  the 
fraction, 

10.7  -f  10.1  +  10.3  -f-  •  •  •  +  (the  nth  observation) 

divided  by  n  (where  the  numerator  contains  the  sum  of  your  scale 
readings),  when  n  is  increased  without  limit?  Each  reading  bears 
no  necessary  relation  to  its  predecessor  or  to  its  successor.  Each  one 
is  accidental  and  for  any  finite  number  of  readings,  which  is  the  most 
you  can  take,  the  arithmetical  mean  is  accidental  too.  And  so  I 
assert  that  it  is  meaningless  to  speak  of  the  limit  of  such  a  series. 
Or  to  state  the  general  truth,  of  which  this  case  is  a  simple  exem- 
plification, the  real  object  of  perception  can  not  be  conceived  as 
Grenzbegriff  or  as  the  limit  of  a  series  of  approximations.  What 
these  conflicting  observations  betray  is  the  presence  of  a  mind  as  an 
essential  part  of  the  total  situation  and  not  the  presence  of  an  ab- 
solute object.3 

If  there  is  no  absolute  object,  no  more  can  the  mechanical  sys- 
tem, in  which  objects  are  found,  be  taken  to  be  absolute.  Thus  it 
is  not  uncommonly  supposed  that,  while  the  future  is  in  some  small 
measure  under  man's  control,  the  past  must  remain  irrevocable  and 
quite  unchanged.  "What  is  past  is  past,"  and  "what  has  happened 
has  happened,"  are  the  tautologies,  which  are  supposed  to  force 
this  truth  upon  us.  No  doubt  at  all  about  the  tautology  itself.  But 
what  is  past  and  what  has  happened  are  exactly  the  matters  which 
ever  have  been  and  will  ever  be  in  dispute,  world  without  end. 
Having  gone  thus  far  I  am  quite  prepared  to  go  further  and  I  shall 
venture  to  assert  that  the  past  is  no  more  irrevocably  determined 
than  is  the  future.  It  is  just  as  plastic,  just  as  amenable  to  our 

s  See  the  article,  ' '  A  Spirit  which  Includes  the  Community, ' '  this  JOURNAL, 
Vol.  XVIII,  No.  18. 


1  •_'  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

interpretations.  What  was  the  azoic  age,  you  may  well  say,  when 
no  one  was  there  to  observe  it?  An  sick  it  was  like  nothing  so  much 
as  nothing  at  all.  It  all  depends  upon  what  observer  you  imagine 
to  have  been  present.  It  is  nothing,  if  not  the  product  of  his  ex- 
perience and  his  reflection.  To  the  soul  of  Empedocles,  seated  it 
may  be  these  two  millenniums  on  the  rim  of  Saturn,  it  has  seemed, 
you  may  be  sure,  a  mingling  and  unminpling  of  the  four  elements, 
earth,  air,  fire  and  water,  guided  by  the  opposite  principles  of  love 
and  hate.  To  the  "Copernicus  of  antiquity"  and  some  of  the 
later  Pythagoreans  it  would  have  had  a  heliocentric  cast,  and  to 
Newton  it  would  have  been  without  doubt  a  collection  of  masses 
attracting  one  another  directly  as  the  product  and  inversely  as  the 
square  of  the  distance  between  their  centers.  Not  only  is  the  past 
plastic  in  the  same  sense  in  which  the  future  is  plastic,  but  it  is 
ever  being  made  to  conform  more  and  more  to  deep-lying  human 
desires.  I  mean,  too,  that  these  desires,  being  as  often  as  not  mis- 
guided, are  as  constantly  being  given  up  in  the  light  of  an  experi- 
ence that  is  ever  enriching  itself. 

There  remains  the  question:  what  is  the  place  of  consciousness 
in  a  world  thus  mechanically  ordered?  Our  answer  must  be  brief, 
for  the  argument  is  already  well  known.  Let  one  illustration  suf- 
fice. I  am  quite  unaware,  of  course,  physiologically  speaking,  what 
a  "prick"  of  conscience  may  turn  out  to  be.  In  order  to  have  be- 
fore us  a  concrete  example,  which  in  the  case  contemplated  is  to 
speak  medicynically,  let  be  granted  that  a  "prick"  of  conscience  is 
the  same  thing  as  a  spasm  along  a  yard  or  two  of  the  intestinal 
tract.  Does  any  one  suppose  that  the  owner  of  this  "apparatus" 
of  conscience  is  the  only  one  in  a  position  to  observe  the  significance 
of  its  behavior?  No  doubt  he  is  favorably  "placed"  to  interpret 
it  as  a  summons  to  action  of  some  appropriate  sort.  But  is  he  the 
only  one  in  a  position  to  offer  judgment?  In  point  of  fact  the  op- 
posite is  very  frequently  the  case.  His  physician,  or  it  may  be  his 
father  confessor,  who  is  privy  to  some  shady  financial  transaction 
of  his,  may  easily  diagnose  his  case  better  than  he  can  judge  it  him- 
self. He  may  not  even  recognize  his  persistent  malady  as  a  prick 
of  conscience  at  all.  His  physician,  or  his  friend,  it  may  be,  recom- 
mends him  to  go  and  do  otherwise;  his  malady  disappears  and  is 
followed  by  a  peace  which  surpasses  even  that  small  understanding 
which  he  has  of  himself  and  his  world.  It  is  nowise  affirmed  that 
a  physiological  description  of  what  a  prick  of  conscience  may  be 
exhausts  all  of  the  meaning  therein  contained,  for  such  a  happen- 
ing may  have  far-reaching  social  and  esthetic  consequences.  Set 
down  in  New  England  and  become  universally  "bred  in  the  bone," 


THE  ANCIENT  LANDMARKS  493 

it  may  be  fairly  decisive  of  the  character  of  a  literature  and  of  the 
domestic  habits.  A  spasm  along  a  yard  or  two  of  the  intestinal 
tract  may  or  may  not  be  a  great  deal  more  than  just  that.  This 
simple  view,  that  more  than  mechanism  can  be  seen  in  a  world  seen 
to  be  mechanically  ordered,  will  yield  an  answer,  I  think,  to  all  of 
Mr.  Lovejoy's  five  conundrums. 

HENRY  BRADFORD  SMITH. 
UNIVERSITY  OP  PENNSYLVANIA. 


THE  ANCIENT  LANDMARKS :   A  COMMENT  ON 
SPIRITUALISTIC  MATERIALISM 

"Kemove  not  the  ancient  landmark."    Proverbs,  XXII;   28. 

"  Philonous.  Tell  me,  Hylas,  hath  every  one  a  liberty  to  change  the  current 
proper  signification  annexed  to  a  common  name  in  any  language?  For 
example,  suppose  a  traveller  should  tell  you,  that  in  a  certain  country  men 
might  pasa  unhurt  through  the  fire;  and  .  .  .  you  found  he  meant  by  the 
word  fire  that  which  others  call  water.  .  .  .  Would  you  call  this  reasonable? 

"Hylas.    No;  I  should  think  it  very  absurd.     Common  custom  is  standard  of 

propriety  in  language.    And  for  any  man  to  affect  speaking  improperly,  is 

to  pervert  the  use  of  speech  and  can  never  serve  to  a  better  purpose  than 

to  protract  and  multiply  disputes  where  there  is  no  difference  of  opinion." 

— Berkeley,  Dialogues  between  Hylas  and  Phttonous,  II. 

In  my  recent  philosophical  wanderings  I  have  met  a  surprising 
number  of  travellers  who  seem  to  mean  "by  the  word  fire  that  which 
others  call  water."  I  have,  for  example,  encountered,  in  the  suc- 
cessive spring  numbers  of  the  Philosophical  Review,  two  who  appear 
to  me  to  play  very  fast  and  loose  with  the  terms  "spiritual"  and 
"material."  (i)  One  of  these,  Professor  Sheldon,  writes  in  defense 
of  what  he  calls  "positive"  or  "enlightened"  materialism,1  though 
he  fills  the  greater  number  of  his  pages  with  "the  indictment  of 
materialism"2  of  the  popular  type,  the  description  of  mind  and 
consciousness  ' '  in  terms  of  physical  process. " 3  In  these  pages  Dr. 
Sheldon  sets  forth  what  he  calls  "the  definite  incompatibilities  be- 
tween admitted  facts  of  consciousness  and  .  .  .  material  process."4 
Of  the  specific  properties  of  consciousness  which  are  incompatible  with 
the  conditions  of  material  reality  he  especially  stresses  the  following : 
first,  the  "presence  of  the  past  in  memory"; 5  second,  the  annihila- 

i ' '  The  Soul  and  Matter, "  by  W.  H.  Sheldon.  Bead  as  the  President  'e 
Address  at  the  December,  1921,  meeting  of  the  American  Philosophical  Associa- 
tion (Eastern  Division).  Philosophical  Review,  1922,  XXXI,  pp.  103-134. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  1102. 

sibid.,  p.  109s. 

*  Pp.  1282  et  al. 

B  Pp.  110*  f. 


•I'.M  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

tion  of  distance,  in  the  perception  of  far-away  objects ;  *  third,  the 
fact  that  "in  selective  attention  what  physically  is,  psychically  is 
not";7  fourth,  the  effectiveness  of  the  future  event  in  purposed 
action;8  finally,  the  "self-continuing"  aspect  of  pleasure"  and 
the  self-checking  tendency  of  pain.10  The  first  three  of  these 
are  "incompatibilities  of  cognition"  from  which  Sheldon  derives 
the  conception  of  mind  as  "a  unity  both  inclusive  and  exclusive,  or 
preferential."11  From  the  incompatibilities  of  affection-conation 
he  argues  that  mind  possesses  "an  organic  systematic  character  that 
makes  [it]  into  an  independent  agent."11  For  he  rightly  insists 
that  "there  are  no  impersonal  bits  of  consciousness,"  that  "there 
is  no  consciousness  that  has  not  selfhood";12  and  he  stresses  over 
and  over  again  "that  individuality  which  constitutes  a  self."18 
His  general  conclusion  is  that  "materialism,  conceived  in  exclusive 
terms,  denying  unique  spiritual  being,  is  false. ' ' 14 

But  at  this  point  Sheldon's  argument  makes  a  sharp  turn.  He 
reminds  us  that  the  mind  "occupies  space  and  time,"  that  "it  acts 
upon  the  external  world,"  that  "it  resides  in  living  organisms  and 
extends  itself  far  beyond  the  limits  of  those  organisms,  without  los- 
ing its  place  in  the  latter."  "  The  student  of  philosophy  will  recog- 
nize this  as  little  other  than  Henry  More's  conception  of  the  extend- 
edness  of  spirit.  But  Sheldon,  so  far  from  concluding  that  exten- 
sion is  spiritual,  teaches  explicitly  that  "mind  is  material,  because 
it  displays  all  the  positive  attributes  of  matter, ' '  that  while  ' '  dualism 
is  right  in  declaring  that  mind  as  compared  with  the  matter  of  our 
sense-world  is  unique;  dualism  and  spiritualism  are  quite  wrong 
.  .  .  when  they  deny  materiality  and  substantiality  to  mind. ' ' ie 
And  he  enlarges  this  initial  doctrine  of  mind  as  "material"  by  a 
hypothetical  conception  of  matter  in  a  new  sense.  "There  might 
be,"  he  says,  "a  kind  of  body  which  .  .  .  would  be  material  be- 
cause it  offers  resistance  and  possesses  inertia"  which  would  yet 
"have  one  surface  in  two  places  at  once";  and  "there  might  well 
be  atoms,"  unlike  those  "which  the  evidence  of  sense  observation 
leads  us  to  believe  in  ...  equally  material,  because  equally  potent 

« Pp.  112*  f. 

^  P.  117». 
«P.  118. 
•  P.  1243. 

10  P.  126». 

11  P.  128«. 
"P.  128». 
is  P.  1162. 

i«  P.  128*.     Cf.  p.  132i. 
"  P.  132i. 
132i. 


THE  ANCIENT  LANDMARKS  495 

in  controlling  the  motions  of  other  atoms,  which  exercise  their  powers 
in  many  places  at  once. ' ' 17 

The  theory  thus  briefly  summarized  is  immensely  significant  in 
its  stress  on  the  substantiality  and  individuality  of  mind  and  in 
its  call  upon  "a  spiritualistic  psychology"  for  a  statement  of  the 
"precise  laws"  of  mind.18  As  enlightened  materialism  the  doctrine 
may,  to  be  sure,  be  challenged  at  several  points.  One  may,  for 
example,  call  attention  to  Sheldon's  unargued  identification  of 
the  "physical"  with  the  material 19  and  to  his  parallel  claim  of  "the 
evidence  of  sense  observation"  for  materialism.20  Or  again,  one 
may  point  out  that  so  long  as  Sheldon  "deliberately"  neglects  to 
take  into  account  personalistic  philosophy 21  he  can  hardly  argue 
that  his  "enlightened  materialism,  freed  from  the  negations  .  .  . 
men  have  read  into  it,  forms  the  only  warrant  of  subtantiality  to 
the  self. ' ' 22  For  substantiality,  in  the  sense  of  persistence  through 
change,  is  precisely  one  of  the  characters  of  the  personalist's  self. 
But  the  main  purpose  of  the  present  paper  is  neither  to  emphasize 
the  significance  of  Sheldon's  rediscovery  of  mind  nor  to  criticize  his 
doctrine  of  its  extendedness  but  simply  to  challenge  his  right  to  the 
term  "materialism"  as  descriptive  of  his  doctrine.  For  Sheldon's 
conception  of  "the  absolute  reality  of  both  matter  and  mind"23  is, 
as  he  himself  sometimes  recognizes, 24  a  form  of  dualism.  And  cer- 
tainly a  philosophy  which  begins  by  arguing  the  existence  of  unique 
spiritual  being  is  not  materialism  in  the  sense  which  the  usage  of 
centuries  has  given  to  the  word;  a  doctrine  which  "forms  the  only 
warrant  of  substantiality  to  the  self"  is  neither  "positive"  nor 
"enlightened"  materialism.  Anybody  with  a  vestige  of  respect  for 
"ancient  landmarks"  in  language  will  protest  to  the  end  against 
this  "perversion  of  the  use  of  speech." 

(ii)  Professor  Sheldon,  as  has  appeared,  seeks  to  materialize 
the  mind.  The  aim  of  Professor  Loewenberg  is,  on  the  contrary,  to 
spiritualize  matter. 25  This  feat  he  readily  accomplishes  by  the 
simple  device,  on  which  his  whole  argument  turns,  of  identifying  the 
"spiritual"  with  the  "valued,"  or  "significant."  Thus  he  refers 
to  "meaning,  significance,  dignity,  rationality — in  short,  spiritual- 

"  Pp.  1302-131. 
is  Op.  oit.,  p.  133. 
i»  Pp.  131i  et  a\ 

20  p.  13H.    Cf.  p.  1332  et  al. 

21  p.  1063. 

22P.1291.     Italics  mine. 

23  P.  1333. 

2*  P.  129i. 

25  cf.  J.  Loewenberg,  ' '  The  Apotheosis  of  Mind  in  Modern  Idealism, ' ' 
Philosophical  Eeview,  1922,  XXXI,  pp.  215  ff. 


}'.»•;  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ity";*8  and  he  explicitly  uses  "spirituality"  as  synonym  for  "con- 
gruity  with  ideals."*7  Once  this  meaning  is  attached  to  the  term, 
Loewenberg  brilliantly  demonstrates  that  mind  may  be  "essentially 
unspiritual"  *•  and  that  "matter  is  capable  of  sublimation  as  much 
as  is  mind."  *'  For  on  the  one  hand,  mind  may  be,  as  Schopenhauer 
describes  it,  "blind,  foolish,  capricious,  sordid  and  miserable";*0 
on  the  other  hand,  materialism  is  "accepted  by  its  votaries"  as  satis- 
fying both  the  spiritual  "sentiment  of  rationality"81  and  "the 
quest  for  unity  .  .  .  behind  and  beyond  the  superficial  medley  and 
flow  of  things."*8 

I  have  no  quarrel  with  these  conclusions.  Like  all  technically 
trained  contemporary  "idealists,"  I  do  not  dream  of  denying  either 
the  "speculative  possibility"  of  a  world  that  is  "through  and 
through  mental,  but  ...  at  variance  with  our  ideals"88  or  the 
fact  that  materialism  may  well  satisfy  genuine  "human  needs"  of 
those  who  hold  it.  Nor  am  I  concerned  with  the  virtual  implications 
of  Dr.  Loewenberg's  closing  paragraphs:  that  philosophy  reduces 
to  a  form  of  differential  psychology  or  to  biography,84  that  "the 
assertions  of  philosophy"  are  essentially  "expressions  of  conflict- 
ing motives  and  needs"  and  that  "the  strife  of  rival  theories  in 
philosophy  is  a  tragic  struggle  not  of  competing  .  .  .  hypotheses  but 
of  incompatible  passions  and  values."85  My  main  purpose  is,  once 
more,  to  protest  against  the  wresting  of  a  word  from  its  time-honored 
meaning.  The  term  "spiritual,"  whatever  the  divagations  in  the 
use  of  it,  has  always  carried  a  meaning  directly  opposed  to  that 
of  "material."  Many  idealists,  doubtless,  before  and  after  and  in- 
cluding Leibniz  and  Berkeley,  have  combined  with  a  spiritualistic 
doctrine  an  uncritical  optimism ;  but,  however  unfounded  their  in- 
ference from  the  mental  nature  of  the  world  to  its  value,  they  have 
not  (to  my  knowledge)  confounded  the  meaning  of  the  term  "spirit- 
ual" with  that  of  "valued,"  or  "significant."  "Spiritual"  means 
simply  "pertaining  to  spirit."  The  ambiguity  in  the  use  of  the 
term  is  due  mainly  to  the  diverse  tendencies  now  to  identify  "spirit" 
(after  Berkeley's  fashion)  «•  with  "mind,"  "soul,"  and  "self," 

"Op.  cit.,  p.  219. 

"  Op.  cit.,  p.  218i.    Cf.  pp.  2173,  230. 

a«  P.  219  el  al. 

*•  P.  229. 

»«  P.  219. 

•i  P.  229. 

«  Pp.  2301-231. 

»»  P.  218. 

8*  This  ia  the  writer  '0  inference,  not  a  statement  of  Loewenberg  himself. 

»•  P.  236. 

»«  Cf.    Principle*  of  Human  Knowledge,  II. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  497 

again  to  limit  the  meaning  of  spirit  and  to  denote  by  the  word, 
"mind  (or  self)  in  its  higher  reaches."  In  either  of  these  uses, 
however,  the  spiritual  is  roughly  speaking  the  personal  and,  as  such, 
sharply  distinguished  from  the  material. 37  Dr.  Loewenberg's  es- 
sential conclusions  are,  of  course,  unaffected  by  this  criticism  of  his 
use  of  terms.  But,  stripped  of  its  paradoxical  and  unhistorical  iden- 
tification of  "spiritual"  and  "material,"  this  portion  of  his  paper, 
it  would  seem,  reduces  to  a  dispute  "where  there  is  no  difference  of 
opinion." 

MARY  WHITON  CALKINS. 
WELLESLEY  COLLEGE. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  Nature  of  Existence.    Volume  I.    J.  M.  E.  MCTAGGART.    Cam- 
bridge University  Press.    1921.    Pp.  xxi -f  309. 

There  are  some  systematic  works,  even  works  of  philosophy,  that 
may  be  read  as  a  sort  of  austere  recreation.  They  may  be 
read  for  the  sheer  pleasure  of  watching  the  thought  sprout 
and  grow  in  this  direction  and  in  the  other.  We  are  saying  a  great 
deal  about  Dr.  McTaggart's  new  work  when  we  say  that  it  can  not 
be  included  in  this  class.  If  there  is  any  one  who  has  the  gift  of  mak- 
ing crooked  paths  straight  and  reducing  an  obscure  or  complex  argu- 
ment to  absolute  lucidity,  it  is  the  author  of  this  work.  Nevertheless, 
there  are  passages,  whole  chapters  indeed,  in  The  Nature  of  Exist- 
ence, where  the  reading  is  about  as  fluent  as  the  middle  chapter  of 
a  Symbolic  Logic.  All  has  been  done,  one  feels,  that  language 
can  do ;  yet  the  thought  itself  is  so  involved  that,  as  Professor  Broad 
has  said,  "it  is  a  remarkable  achievement  for  a  writer  to  have  kept 
his  head  among  all  these  complexities  without  the  help  of  an  elaborate 
symbolism. ' ' 

That  this  difficulty  may  not  be  found  in  the  forthcoming  second 
volume  of  the  work  is  suggested  by  the  author's  statement  of  his 
plan.  In  the  first  volume  he  considers  "what  can  be  determined  as 
to  the  characteristics  which  belong  to  all  that  exists,  or,  again,  which 
belong  to  existence  as  a  whole."  In  the  second  volume  he  proposes 
to  consider  "what  consequences  of  theoretical  and  practical  interest 
can  be  drawn  from  this  general  nature  of  the  existent  with  respect 
to  various  parts  of  the  existent  which  are  empirically  known  to  us. ' ' 
Throughout  this  first  book  the  reasoning  is  rigorously  a  priori.  There 
are  only  two  occasions  on  which  Dr.  McTaggart  makes  any  appeal  to 
perception :  once  to  prove  that  something  exists,  and  again  to  prove 

37  Since  Hume  wrote,  the  term  ' '  spiritual ' '  has  served  also  to  differentiate 
the  personalistic  from  the  ideistic  form  of  idealism. 


498  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

that  this  something  is  not  simple;  and  even  of  these  cases,  it  is  only 
in  the  former  that  he  feels  such  appeal  to  be  necessary.  This  resolute 
adherence  to  the  a  priori  is  not  in  metaphysics  a  matter  of  choice, 
he  contends;  it  is  a  matter  of  necessity.  When  the  question  is  what 
characteristics  belong  to  everything  that  exists,  or  to  existence  as  a 
whole,  the  use  of  induction  is  absurd.  Induction  proceeds  by  noting 
the  resemblances  among  the  members  of  a  class:  but  existence  as  a 
whole  is  not  a  member  of  a  class  of  such  existences.  Again,  the  num- 
ber of  existent  things  is  infinite,  and  hence  no  possible  inductive  dili- 
gence could  bring  within  its  purview  more  than  "an  infinitely  small 
proportion  of  the  whole. "  This  abjuring  of  sense  experience  and  ad- 
herence to  "the  high  priori  road"  naturally  suggests  Hegel;  and 
while  Dr.  McTaggart  is  careful  to  distinguish  his  own  method  from 
the  Hegelian,  he  admits  that  it  stands  "much  closer  to  Hegel's 
method  than  to  that  of  any  other  philosopher."  He  is  so  entirely 
unimpressed  with  the  arguments  that  have  been  brought  against  the 
fertility  of  the  deductive  method  in  metaphysics  that  he  offers  only 
a  very  brief  defense,  and  refers  the  reader  to  the  answer  that  has 
been  given  by  "Mr.  Bradley  in  a  passage  which  I  regard  as  by  far 
the  most  important  and  illuminating  comment  ever  made  upon 
Hegel."1 

Some  of  McTaggart 's  chief  positions  may  be  set  in  relief  by  a 
comparison  with  those  of  the  contemporary  to  whom  he  here  so  ap- 
provingly refers.  Bradley,  as  well  as  McTaggart,  is  a  metaphysician 
who  still  believes  that  final  truth  may  be  gained  by  the  speculative 
route  about  the  nature  of  reality  and  the  nature  of  truth  itself.  Both 
believe  that  "nothing  exists  but  spirit."  Both  emphasize  the  dis- 
tinction between  "what"  and  "that,"  the  "nature"  of  a  thing  and 
its  existence.  Both  maintain  that  neither  of  these  sides  can  be 
without  the  other ;  and  they  would  hence  agree  that  such  entities  as 
propositions,  possibilities  and  ' '  floating  ideas, ' '  if  regarded — as  many 
realists  would  regard  them — as  real  but  non-existent,  are  quite  gra- 
tuitous. Both  would  regard  every  judgment  as  ultimately  a  judg- 
ment of  existence,  and  all  reality  as  ultimately  existent.  It  is  no  doubt 
because  he  holds  this  view  that  Dr.  McTaggart  has  given  his  work 
the  title  that  it  bears,  since  in  studying  what  exists  he  considers  that 
he  is  examining  the  character  of  all  that  is  real.  Both  thinkers,  again, 
agree  in  the  doctrine  of  degrees  of  truth  and  would  hold  that  since 
the  nature  of  a  thing  is  not  independent  of  its  relations  to  other 
things,  our  conception  of  it  must  change  as  its  relations  are  more 
completely  apprehended.  And  though  Bradley 's  sweeping  disbelief 
in  the  reality  of  all  relations  would  set  him  at  last  apart  from  Mc- 

»  Logic,  Book  III,  Pt.  I,  Ch.  II,  E. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  499 

Taggart,  both,  would  hold  that  our  knowledge  approaches  perfection 
in  the  degree  to  which  we  lay  hold  of  an  order  of  necessity  which  in- 
volves everything  in  its  web. 

But  with  this  general  agreement,  there  are  striking  points  of 
difference  which  appear  at  the  outset  of  McTaggart's  work.  It  is 
evident,  for  example,  that  neither  reality  nor  truth  means  to  him 
what  it  does  to  Bradley.  For  while  McTaggart  would  admit  degrees 
of  truth,  he  would  deny  that  there  can  be  any  degrees  of  the  real. 
"  'A  is  X'  may  misrepresent  the  nature  of  A  less  than  'A  is  Y/  but, 
unless  it  is  quite  true  that  A  is  X,  then  A  is  not  X,  and  AX  is  not 
real  at  all"  (p.  5).  Again,  what  constitutes  the  truth  of  a  belief  is 
not  its  coherence  with  a  system  of  beliefs,  but  its  correspondence  with 
the  specific  fact  about  which  it  is  entertained.  Correspondence  does 
not  mean  copying ;  but  while  we  can  say  what  it  is  not,  and  can  point 
to  examples  of  it,  we  are  unable  to  say  what  it  is;  it  is  a  relation 
which  is  unique  and  therefore  undefinable.  It  is  this  difference  of 
view  regarding  the  relation  of  judgment  to  reality  which  explains, 
I  think,  the  other  difference  just  noted.  In  Bradley 's  view  the 
reality  judged  about  is  actually  present  in  judgment;  "the  real 
Caesar  beyond  doubt  must  himself  enter  into  my  judgments  and  be  a 
constituent  of  my  knowledge. ' ' 2  There  is  no  external  and  real  object 
to  which  my  judgment,  if  true,  must  correspond.  My  judgment  is 
reality  affirming  itself  in  part  through  my  mind.  Truth  and  reality 
become  identical,  and  hence  the  degrees  of  each  are  the  same.  But 
for  one  who  holds  that  the  content  of  judgment  is  distinct  from  the 
fact  referred  to,  and  that  the  truth  of  the  one  is  quite  distinct  from 
the  reality  of  the  other,  it  is  clear  that  a  judgment  may  become  more 
true  without  the  fact's  becoming  more  real.  Indeed,  since  truth 
belongs  to  beliefs,  and  beliefs  are  psychical  events  which  are  con- 
tinually coming  and  going,  truth  too  must  come  and  go.  Thus  a 
fact  may  be  real  but  can  not  be  true;  while  a  judgment  or  belief  may 
be  true,  but  except  in  its  character  as  psychical  event,  apparently 
not  real.  If  I  dream  of  Mrs.  Gamp,  my  dream  itself  is  real,  but 
Mrs.  Gamp  is  not;  and  if  Mrs.  Gamp  were  real,  that  reality  would 
belong  to  her  and  not  to  any  judgment  about  her.  And  reality,  like 
existence,  is  either  there  or  not  there.  Indeed,  although  McTaggart 
distinguishes  the  existent  as  prima  facie  only  a  species  of  the  real, 
it  seems  to  me  that  throughout  he  means  by  "real"  "existing"  and 
nothing  more. 

Perhaps  the  most  interesting  feature  of  Dr.  McTaggart's  discus- 
sion of  truth  is  its  incidental  criticism  of  the  doctrine  of  proposi- 
tions. These,  he  maintains,  are  needless  intermediaries  between 

2  Essays  on  Truth  and  Seality,  p.  409. 


500  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

thought  and  fact,  and  on  principles  of  economy  may  be  eliminated. 

All  cases  both  of  true  and  false  beliefs  he  thinks  sufficiently  covered 

1  y  the  formulae  that  truth  is  correspondence  with  the  fact  referred 

iiid  that  falsity  is  a  relation  of  non-correspondence  to  all  facts. 

The  argument  of  this  volume,  after  the  introductory  book,  is  at 
once  so  compact  and  so  complex  that  nothing  beyond  an  indication  of 
the  trend  of  the  argument  is  here  feasible.  Having  proved  that 
"something  exists"  by  showing  in  Cartesian  style  that  to  doubt  it 
involves  the  existence  of  the  doubt,  and  having  shown  that  existence 
without  qualitative  content  is  meaningless,  the  author  maintains 
that  all  qualities  belong  to  substances,  substance  being  defined  as 
"something  existent  which  has  qualities  without  being  itself  a  qual- 
ity." A  substance  is  infinitely  divisible,  and  since  each  part  is  also 
a  substance,  the  number  of  substances  is  infinite;  while,  further, 
the  nature  of  each  is  distinct.  The  author's  main  problem  is  now 
to  determine  the  types  of  relation  which  bind  substances  and  their 
qualities  together.  Of  these  perhaps  the  most  important  are  what 
McTaggart  terms  intrinsic  and  extrinsic  determination;  the  first 
of  which  is  the  implication  between  characteristics  in  virtue  of  which 
inference  is  possible,  and  the  second  of  which  is  a  relation  of  inter- 
dependence which  unites  every  quality  and  every  substance  in  such 
a  way  that,  given  the  alteration  of  the  slightest  detail  anywhere, 
we  could  not  with  confidence  expect  anything  to  be  the  same.  With 
this  relation  established,  McTaggart  proceeds  at  once  to  the  con- 
tention that  the  universe  is  an  "organic  unity,"  a  conception  which 
(probably  with  memories  of  the  bitter  history  of  the  term)  he  takes 
a  separate  chapter  to  define.  The  last  division  of  the  book  is  de- 
voted largely  to  the  working  out  of  a  very  elaborate  relation  called 
"determining  correspondence"  between  the  various  substances  in  the 
universe,  a  relation  which  is  devised  to  meet,  and  which  McTaggart 
believes  does  meet,  the  contradiction  apparently  presented  by  the 
infinite  divisibility  of  substance. 

It  seems  likely  that  this  work  will  first  gain  its  proper  estimation 
at  the  hands  of  that  increasing  group  of  thinkers  who  are  at  home 
on  the  borders  of  mathematics  and  philosophy  rather  than  from 
those  who  have  confined  themselves  to  the  more  traditional  modes  of 
thought.  Whatever  their  verdict,  it  is  clear  that  Dr.  McTaggart 
has  given  us  one  of  the  most  lucidly  written,  thoroughgoing  and 
competent  books  on  metaphysics  that  have  appeared  in  many  a  year. 

BRAND  BLANSHARD. 

UNIVERSITY  or  MICHIGAN. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  501 

The  Truths  We  Live  By.  J.  WILLIAM  HUDSON.  New  York :  D.  Apple- 
ton  &  Co.  1921.  Pp.  x  +  308. 

A  presentation  of  truths  we  live  by  need  not  be  startling.  On 
the  contrary,  a  veracious  work  of  art  makes  us  feel  at  home.  "We 
recognize  its  truths  as  old  friends  and  commend  its  essential  trite- 
ness. There  is  a  sense  of  familiarity  but  of  a  different  sort,  to  be 
had  from  reading  Professor  Hudson's  book.  It  continues  a  phil- 
osophic tradition  but  lacks  the  feeling  of  reality. 

It  is  addressed  to  men  and  women  "who  have  not  specialized  in 
philosophy,  and  are,  nevertheless,  interested  in  life's  greater  prob- 
lems" (p.  x).  It  proposes  to  forward  moral  reconstruction  by  at- 
tacking a  certain  current  skepticism  which  adduces  the  findings  of 
science  and  the  history  of  morals  as  evidence  that  no  ideals  are 
absolutely  valid. 

The  conflict  over  the  comparative  value  of  such  specific  ideals 
as  self-sacrifice  and  pleasure,  Mr.  Hudson  disposes  of  by  the  argu- 
ment that  "all  conflicting  moral  ideals  imply  a  moral  end  that  in- 
cludes them  all  and  transcends  every  one  of  them"  (p.  27).  This 
end  may  be  called  self -realization. 

His  second  and  larger  aim  is  to  show  that  the  beliefs  necessary 
to  moral  confidence  are  as  certain  as  the  presuppositions  of  science 
and  are  arrived  at  in  the  same  way.  They  are  outside  the  range 
of  specific  sciences  but  are  as  demonstrable  as  scientific  laws  are. 

He  says,  "We  justify  the  great  underlying  laws  of  science,  such 
as  the  Law  of  Universal  Causation,  by  the  fact  that  we  want  sci- 
ence ;  we  justify  science  in  turn  through  the  fact  that  we  want  life ' ' 
(p.  107). 

Since  desire  is  the  fundamental  characteristic  of  life,  reason 
must  serve  it  by  accepting  what  it  demands.  The  truths,  there- 
fore, that  are  necessary  for  a  moral  life  must  be  received  in  the 
same  way  that  the  scientist  assumes  Universal  Causation.  Mr. 
Hudson  thinks  there  are  four  beliefs  which  are  thus  "demonstra- 
ble." 

The  first  of  these  is  the  belief  "that  the  universe  is  at  bottom  a 
moral  order ;  that  is,  an  order  in  which  righteousness  will  certainly 
triumph  or  at  any  rate  has  a  chance  to  triumph"  (p.  53).  For  the 
purpose  of  the  argument  this  latter  reservation  is  dropped  and  we 
are  told  that  "we  are  to  believe  in  the  utter  triumph  of  the  good 
if  our  moral  confidence  is  to  be  sure;  and  it  must  be  sure"  (p.  55). 
Such  confidence  involves  belief  in  personal  immortality,  in  God  and 
in  freedom  of  the  will. 

The  will  to  live,  which  is  at  the  center  of  the  evolutionary  proc- 
ess, becomes,  in  human  beings,  the  will  to  live  a  specific  kind  of  life. 


502  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

And  the  ideal  life  of  perfect  goodness,  truth,  and  beauty  for  which 
men  strive  requires  infinity  for  its  development.  Immortality  is 
thus  one  of  the  great  verities. 

Analysis  of  the  idea  of  God  turns,  in  Mr.  Hudson's  mind,  into 
a  demonstration  that  God  is  real,  not  only  ideally,  but  existentially, 
"as  you  and  I  are  real"  (p.  175). 

The  ideal  is  a  dynamic  good  which  includes  the  struggle  to  reach 
it;  it  includes  nature,  since  nature  is  not  wholly  indifferent  to 
man's  uses;  and  it  is  the  ideal  for  all  humanity.  Professor  Hud- 
son's unexpected  conclusion  is,  "The  Perfection  we  seek  is  the  in- 
finite Series  of  our  deeds  including  all  of  nature  and  the  lives  of 
all  our  fellows"  (pp.  182-183). 

"This  'totality  of  things'  suddenly  emerges  as  something  more 
than  that  God  which  science  gives  us  under  that  phrase.  It  is  no 
longer,  rightly  interpreted,  a  mere  aggregate  of  facts  .  .  .  but  it 
is  a  moral  order,  a  Life,  realizing  itself  through  infinite  time"  (p. 
183). 

To  the  belief  in  immortality  and  God,  thus  achieved,  Mr.  Hud- 
son adds  the  conviction  that  our  wills  are  absolutely  free.  If  we 
are  to  be  held  accountable  for  our  deeds  we  must  have  the  power 
of  freely  choosing  ' '  regardless  of  previous  events  in  the  outer  world, 
in  spite  of  our  previous  character  and  of  all  the  experiences  that 
have  tended  to  make  us  what  we  are  up  to  date"  (p.  228).  For 
such  choosing,  Mr.  Hudson  is  forced  to  conceive  of  an  ego  behind 
the  scenes.  In  order  that  it,  in  turn,  may  be  free  from  any  taint 
of  influence,  'he  says  we  may  think  of  it  as  uncreated  and  co-eternal 
with  God. 

The  argument  will  doubtless  be  convincing  to  many  of  the  read- 
ers to  whom  it  is  addressed.  The  painstaking  care  with  which  it  is 
presented  will  perhaps  nullify  the  effect  of  the  unexpected  con- 
clusions which  so  often,  to  use  Mr.  Hudson's  own  word,  emerge. 
Some  of  the  most  evident  objections  to  his  argument  the  author 
has  met.  He  admits  his  proof  to  be  dialectical  but  denies,  quite 
correctly,  that  he  sanctions  any  belief  which  we  merely  wish  to  ac- 
cept. He  has  shown  what  many  "moderns"  need  to  remember, 
that  the  science  which  is  quoted  as  authority  in  every  field  of  hu- 
man thought  has  in  reality  nothing  to  offer  upon  many  subjects  of 
the  utmost  importance.  This  merely  means  that  intelligent  in- 
vestigation still  has  something  to  do.  It  does  not  mean  that  we 
must  have  recourse  to  dialectic  in  order  to  discover  the  facts  of  ex- 
istence. 

Mr.  Hudson's  argument  is  confused  whenever  it  touches  upon 
the  nature  and  validity  of  scientific  hypothesis.  It  is  true  that 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  503 

science  is  justified  as  a  human  pursuit  only  if  it  contributes  to  hu- 
man well-being;  that  fact,  however,  is  neither  the  basis  nor  the 
justification  for  its  hypotheses.  Speaking  with  tongues  might  be 
justified  on  the  grounds  of  edification;  its  deliverances  would  be, 
none  the  less,  nonsense. 

Again,  when  he  speaks  of  ideals,  Professor  Hudson's  argument 
is  not  clear.  He  sees  that  human  desire  is  the  first  word  in  the 
moral  life  and  that  harmony  is  the  form  which  the  good  life  will 
take.  Yet  he  falls  back  into  an  absolutism  which  can  conceive 
"only  one  Perfect."  Furthermore,  he  is  not  content  to  let  ideals 
be  ideal.  God  must  exist. 

Professor  Hudson  has  attempted  to  clarify  popular  ideas  of  the 
relation  of  science  and  ethics,  but  his  contribution  misses  its  aim 
because  it  is  based  upon  a  confusion  in  method.  The  most  signifi- 
cant parts  of  his  book  are  the  distinctions  which  he  makes  and  then 
ignores. 

NEW  YORK  CITY. 

MARY  SHAW. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  PHILOSOPHICAL  REVIEW.  XXXI,  4.  July,  1922.  Valua- 
tion and  Experimental  Knowledge :  John  Dewey.  Humor  and  Bosan- 
quet's  Theory  of  Experience:  Katherine  Gilbert.  Possession  and 
Individuality:  E.  Jordan.  An  Approach  to  Idealism:  Frank  E. 
Morris.  Rosmini,  Bonatelli,  and  Varisco,  on  Consciousness:  James 
Lindsay. 

REVUE  PHILOSOPHIQUE.  XLVII,  7-8.  July-August,  1922. 
Numero  exceptionnel :  Les  Theories  d 'Einstein  sur  la  Relativite. 
La  signification  philosophique  de  la  theorie  de  la  relativite:  H. 
Reichenbach  (trans,  par  M.  Leon  Block}.  Pour  1'intelligence  de  la 
relativite:  G.  Cerf.  Einstein  et  la  metaphysique :  Ed  Goblot.  Le 
temps  et  1'espace  du  sens  commun  et  les  theories  d 'Einstein:  E. 
Richard-Foy. 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW.  XXIX,  No.  3.  May,  1922.  The  Onto- 
genetic  Significance  of  Instinct,  Habit,  and  Intelligence:  James  L. 
Mursell.  Practical  Logic  and  Color  Theories:  Christine  Ladd- 
Franklin.  The  Significance  of  Psychical  Monism:  Leonard  Tro- 
land.  Synaesthesia,  A  Form  of  Perception :  Raymond  Wheeler 
and  Thomas  Cutsforth.  A  Comparison  of  Mental  Abilities  of  Mixed 
and  Full  Blood  Indians  on  a  Basis  of  Education :  Thomas  R.  Garth. 
Discussion:  Induction  and  Radical  Psychology:  Victor  S.  Tarros. 


504  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Bergson,  Hi-nri:  Duree  et  Simultan&te.  A  propos  de  la 
Th4orie  d 'Einstein.  Paris:  Felix  Alcan.  1922.  viii  +  245  pp. 

Carr,  H.  Wildon :  A  Theory  of  Monads.  Outlines  of  the  Phil- 
osophy of  the  Principle  of  Relativity.  London:  Macmillan  &  Co. 
1922.  350  pp. 

Cox,  George  Clarke :  The  Public  Conscience.  New  York :  Henry 
Holt  &  Co.  1922.  xix  +  483pp.  $3.00. 

Ginsberg,  Morris:  The  Psychology  of  Society.  New  York:  E. 
P.  Dutton  &  Co.  1922.  xvi  -j-  168  pp.  $2.50. 

Nordmann,  Charles:  Einstein  and  the  Universe.  Trans,  by 
Joseph  McCabe.  New  York:  Henry  Holt  &  Co.  1922.  xvi  + 
240  pp.  $2.50. 

NOTES  AND  NEWS 

We  have  received  the  first  number  of  Volume  I  of  the  Arkiv 
for  Psykologi  och  Pedagogik  from  the  Library  of  the  Royal  Univer- 
sity of  Upsala,  Sweden.  The  Arkiv  is  a  continuation  under  a  new 
name  of  the  Revue  Psyke  which  ceased  publication  in  1920. 

During  the  academic  years  1922-23  and  1923-24,  the  Gifford 
Lectures  at  the  University  of  St.  Andrews  will  be  given  by  Professor 
C.  Lloyd  Morgan  of  Bristol.  "Evolution,  Emergent  and  Creative" 
will  be  the  subject  of  these  lectures. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  19  SEPTEMBER  14,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE 
I.  THE  ALLEGED  FUTURITY  OF  YESTERDAY 

I  AM  greatly  obliged  to  Professor  Dewey  for  the  careful  and  ex- 
tended comment1  with  which  he  has  honored  my  contribution 
to  Essays  in  Critical  Realism.  Philosophers  of  eminence  have  not 
always  been  equally  ready  to  enter  the  lists  and  join  issue  directly, 
and  point  by  point,  with  their  critics.  Mr.  Dewey 's  two  papers, 
therefore,  are  an  encouraging  manifestation  of  belief  in  that  con- 
ception of  the  philosophic  quest  of  truth  which  makes  it  consist  in 
an  essentially  social  and  cooperative  process  of  intellectual  experi- 
mentation, wherein  all  philosophical  theses,  arguments  and  distinc- 
tions are  cast  into  the  alembic  of  searching,  patient,  analytic  dis- 
cussion by  many  and  diverse  minds.  I  do  not,  indeed,  find  that,  in 
the  present  instance,  great  progress  has  as  yet  been  accomplished 
towards  actual  agreement.  But  that,  doubtless,  is  a  result  which 
could  hardly  be  expected  after  a  single  exchange  of  views.  Mean- 
while Mr.  Dewey 's  articles  seem  to  me  to  do  a  good  deal  to  make 
more  clear  the  nature,  the  grounds  and  the  causes  of  disagreement. 
And  I  am  hopeful  that  a  continuance  of  the  discussion  may  still 
further  clarify  not  merely  these  matters,  but  the  important  philo- 
sophical issues  which  they  involve. 

"What  those  issues  are  it  is  doubtless  well  to  remind  the  reader. 
In  the  essay  with  which  Mr.  Dewey 's  articles  are  concerned  I  at- 
tempted to  vindicate,  among  others,  the  two  following  theses:  (a) 
that  all  practical  or  instrumental  knowledge  is,  or  at  least  includes 
and  requires,  ' '  presentative "  knowledge,  a  representation  of  not- 
present  existents  by  present  data;  (6)  that  "pragmatically  con- 
sidered, knowledge  is  thus  necessarily  and  constantly  conversant 
with  entities  which  are  existentially  transcendent  of  the  knowing 
experience."  As  the  simplest  and  least  dubitable  example  of  such 

i ' '  Realism  without  Monism  or  Dualism, ' '  this  JOURNAL,  XIX,  pp.  309- 
317,  351-361.  These  papers  will  be  here  cited  as  B.  M.  D.,  and  the  Essays  in 
Critical  Realism  as  E.  C.  R. 

505 


506  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

transcendent  reference,  and  therefore  as  a  crucial  instance,  I  cited 
our  judgments  of  retrospection  and  anticipation.  In  them,  it  seems 
obvious  to  most  men,  we  "mean"  and  know  entities  which  are  not 
directly  given  in  experience  at  the  moment  when  they  are  known, 
inasmuch  as  they  do  not  then  form  a  part  of  the  existing  world. 
In  justifying  both  the  general  theses  mentioned,  and  the  particular 
instance  of  judgments  about  the  past,  I  was  under  the  necessity  of 
controverting  views  which  had  been  expressed  by  Mr.  Dewey  and 
which  seemed  to  me  an  aberration  from  the  true  logic  of  his  own 
pragmatic  doctrine.  Though  not  without  some  ambiguity  of  lan- 
fruage,  he  had  seemed  to  maintain  that  the  object  meant  or  known 
in  valid  judgments  must  always  be  "directly  experienced" — an 
assertion  which,  if  taken  literally,  would  imply  the  impossibility 
of  intertemporal  cognition,  of  the  knowing  of  one  moment's  ex- 
perience at  another  moment.  And  in  fact,  with  respect  to  the 
special  case  of  knowledge  of  the  past,  Mr.  Dewey  had  been  led  by 
his  "principle  of  immediate  empiricism"  into  an  apparent  denial 
of  it.s  possibility.2  Because  the  past  object  is  transcendent  of  the 
experience  that  knows  it,  is  "past  and  gone  forever,"  Mr.  Dewey 
had  in  numerous  passages  betrayed  a  curious  reluctance  to  admit 
that  the  past  as  such  can  be  said  to  be  "known"  or  "meant"  at 
all.  This  paradox  is  in  truth,  as  I  have  previously  contended,  an 
inevitable  consequence  of  the  attempt  to  escape  epistemological 
dualism  by  denying  the  transcendence  of  the  object  known. 

The  same  paradox  the  first  part  of  Mr.  Dewey 's  reply  seems  to 
reaffirm  and  even  sharpen;  for  its  argument  leads  up  to  such  as- 
sertions as:  "the  present  or  future  constitutes  the  object  or  genuine 
meaning  of  the  judgment  about  the  past";8  in  retrospective  judg- 
ments "the  actual  thing  meant,  the  object  of  judgment,  is  pros- 
pective";4 "the  past  occurrence  is  not  the  meaning  of  proposi- 
tions" of  this  type.5  And  since  he  has,  as  he  thinks,  overthrown 
this  supposed  crucial  instance  of  the  transcendent  reference  of 
knowledge.  Mr.  Dewey  concludes  that  he  has  proved  it  "possible 
to  drop  out  the  epistemological  theory  of  mysterious  'transcend- 
ence.' '  While,  for  reasons  to  be  mentioned  later,  I  doubt  whether 
these  propositions  mean  what  they  say,  I  shall  first  assume  that 
they  do  so,  and  shall  review  Mr.  Dewey 's  argument  as  an  attempted 
proof  of  them. 

2  For  example  see  E.  C.  B.,  pp.  42-4,  62-4,  63-71. 

»  See  R.  it.  D.,  p.  313. 

«  B.  M.  D.,  p.  314. 

•  K.  If.  D.,  p.  312;  italics  in  original. 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE  507 

1.  The  first  argument  consists  in  the  contention  that  it  is  "only 
when  the  past  event  which  is  judged  is  a  going  concern  having  ef- 
fects still  directly  observable"  that  "judgment  and  knowledge  are 
possible."     But  this  proposition,  which  is  given  the  emphasis  of 
italics,  is,  I  suppose,  denied  by  no  one;  I,  at  least,  am  far  from 
disputing  it.     Obviously,  the  ground  of  present  belief  must  be  a 
present  ground;  the  evidence  which  can  to-day  justify  a  judgment 
about  yesterday's   events   must    be    evidence    existing  to-day,   not 
yesterday.     Nor  do  I  see  any  objection  to  converting  this  truism 
into  Mr.  Dewey's  proposition  that  "  the  true  object  of  a  judgment 
about  a  past  event  may  be"   (I  should  even  add:  in  the  case  of 
scientifically  verifiable  judgments,  must  be)  "a  past-event-having- 
a-connection-continuing-into-the-present-and-f uture. ' '     Since  we  do 
not  regard  as  now  knowable  (in  the  usual  sense  of  "knowledge") 
past  matters  of  fact  which  have  left  no  now  discoverable  trace  of 
or  witness  to  their  reality,  we  may  properly  enough  say  that  the 
complete  "object"  of  any  genuine  piece  of  verified  knowledge  of 
the  past  is  a  past  having  effects,  direct  or  indirect,  surviving  in  the 
present  (memories  being  included  among  these  effects).     In  other 
words,  continuity — usually  of  the  causal  sort — with  the  present  is 
undeniably  a  part  of  the  meaning  of  the  expression  "known  past 
event. ' '    But  the  part  is  not  the  whole ;  and  it  is  upon  a  distinction 
so  simple  as  this  that  Mr.  Dewey's  first  argument  breaks  down. 
For  the  matter  at  issue  has  to  do  solely  with  that  part  of  the  total 
object  of  a  judgment  about  the  past  which  is  past.     Mr.  Dewey 
seems  to  suppose  that  when  it  is  shown  that  any  valid  and  verified 
retrospective  judgment  contains  at  least  an  implicit  reference  to 
the  present  and  future,  we  are  thereby  relieved  of  all  logical  con- 
cern about  its  primary  reference  to  the  past.    It  is  as  if  an  astrono- 
mer, observing  in  the  spectrum  of  a  star  both  red  and  yellow  rays, 
should  say  to  himself:  "This  red  is  evidently  merely  a  red-in-con- 
nection-with-yellow ;  it  will  therefore  suffice,  in  my  study  of  the 
star,   if  I   consider  only  the  yellow,   disregarding   any   problems 
which  may  have  to  do  solely  with  the  red."    But,  as  Mr.  Dewey's 
own  expressions  inevitably  and  repeatedly  concede,  the  past  refer- 
ence still  remains,  an  essential  aspect  of  the  present  cognitive  ex- 
perience; and  with  it  remains  the  justification  for  the  contention 
of  the  portion  of  my  paper  under  discussion. 

2.  Mr.  Dewey,  however,  seeks  to  justify  the  monopoly  of  his 
philosophic  attention  enjoyed  by  the  present  and  future  part  of  a 
retrospective  judgment's  reference,  by  means  of  a  distinction  be- 
tween "object"  and  "subject-matter";  and  it  is  upon  the  applica- 
tion of  "this  generic  and  indispensable  distinction"  to  that  class 


r,os  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  judgments  that  he  seems  finally  to  rest  his  case.  By  "subject- 
matter"  he  signifies  the  "accepted  considerations"  in  any  inquiry, 
the  tliinirs  known,  or  taken  as  known,  in  order  that  they  may  lead 
to  a  knowledge  of  something  else  which  at  the  outset  of  the  inquiry 
is  not  known.  The  "object"  is  this  something  else,  which  becomes 
a  "thing  known,"  an  accepted  consideration,  at  the  successful  con- 
clusion of  the  inquiry.  Thus  in  a  court  of  law  the  verdict  "con- 
tains the  object,  the  thing  meant;  evidence  presented  and  rules  of 
law  applied  furnish  subject-matter."  The  distinction  itself  is  un- 
exceptionable, though  more  sharply  contrasted  terms  might  have 
been  found  to  express  it;  but  Mr.  Dewey's  way  of  applying  it  "to 
analysis  of  judgments  about  the  past"  seems  to  me  really  very  odd. 
In  such  a  judgment  it  is  "the  nature  of  the  past  event"  which  he 
identifies  with  the  "subject-matter,"  on  the  ground  that  it  is  "re- 
quired to  make  a  reasonable  judgment  about  the  present  or  future"; 
the  latter  "thus  constitutes  the  object  or  genuine  meaning  of  the 
judgment."  Hence,  "there  is  nothing  forced  or  paradoxical  about 
the  view  that  in  all  such  cases  the  actual  thing  meant,  the  ob- 
ject of  judgment,  is  prospective."6  Q.  E.  D.  The  paleontolo- 
gist will  thus  learn,  with  some  surprise,  that  when  he  is  seeking  to 
determine  whether  a  certain  fossil  animal  was  contemporaneous 
with  paleolithic  man,  the  "actual  thing  meant"  by  his  inquiry,  the 
"object  or  genuine  meaning"  of  the  judgment  which  he  reaches 
at  the  end  of  it,  is  not  an  organism  that  has  been  extinct  for  ages, 
nor  even  present  fossil  remains,  but  something  "prospective."  As 
for  that  class  of  judgments  about  the  past  which  are  the  specialty 
of  courts  of  criminal  law,  Mr.  Dewey's  previous  application  (cited 
just  above)  of  his  distinction  to  these  judgments  now  manifestly  re- 
quires not  merely  revision  but  reversal.  In  a  coroner's  inquest, 
for  example,  the  "nature  of  the  past  event"  under  inquiry  is  the 
manner  in  which  the  deceased  came  to  his  death ;  which  is  there- 
fore the  "subject-matter"  of  the  inquiry;  which  in  turn  means,  by 
Mr.  Dewey's  definition,  that  it  constitutes  the  "accepted  considera- 
tions" in  the  case;  while  "the  evidence  presented" — though  it  is 
classified  as  "subject-matter"  only  a  few  lines  earlier  in  Mr. 
Dewey's  paper — must  in  the  light  of  his  present  conclusion  be  re- 
moved from  that  class  (and  so  from  that  of  "accepted  considera- 
tions") and  be  described  as  the  "still  unattained  object"  of  the 
inquiry  1 

«  B.  M.  D.,  pp.  313,  314;  italics  mine.  The  distinction  between  object  and 
subject-matter,  as  here  used,  seems  to  be  merely  another  phrasing  of  that  be- 
tween ' '  reference ' '  and  ' '  content ' '  employed  for  the  same  ends  in  The  Influence 
of  Darwin  upon  Philosophy,  p.  61.  Cf.  my  comment  on  this,  E.  C.  E.,  p.  67. 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE  509 

How  has  it  come  about  that  Mr.  Dewey  thus  reverses,  in  the 
course  of  a  single  page,  the  meaning  of  his  own  terminology  for  ex- 
pressing this  "indispensable  distinction"?     The  origin  of  the  con- 
fusion is  perhaps  not  beyond  the  reach  of  analysis.    If  he  had  ad- 
hered to  his  original  definitions,  it  would  have  been  obvious  that, 
in  any  inquiry  into  the  nature  or  reality  of  a  past  event,  the  "ac- 
cepted considerations,"  and  therefore  the  "subject-matter,"  must, 
as  he  himself  in  other  passages  often  reiterates,  consist  of  present 
data — the  testimony  of  the  witnesses,  the  character  and  situation 
of  the  fossil.     Thus  the  superior  status  of  "object"  would  have 
fallen  to  the  lot  of  the  past  event  to  which  the  inquiry  relates.    This 
result,  however,  would  be  contrary  to  Mr.  Dewey 's  main  thesis ;  and 
consequently,  another  distinction  seems  to  have  been  unconsciously 
substituted  for  the  original  one,  while  the  same  pair  of  terms  is  re- 
tained to  express  it.     The  new  distinction  actually  seems  to  turn 
upon  a  play  on  the  double  meaning  of  the  word  "object."    In  the 
original  distinction  the  word,  of  course,  meant  simply  the  thing 
referred  to  in  a  judgment;  it  now  means  the  purpose  or  interest 
which  leads  one  to  ask  the  question  which  the  judgment  answers: 
"the   object   is  the   fulfilment   of  an   intention."     Thus — as   Mr. 
Dewey  illustrates — if  I  ask  myself  whether  I  mailed  that  letter 
yesterday,  the  "object"  of  my  inquiry  is  to  get  answers  to  such 
questions  of  present  or  future  interest  as  these:  "What  is  the  state 
of  affairs  between  some  other  person  and  myself?    Is  his  letter  ac- 
knowledged or  no;  is  the  deal  closed,  the  engagement  made,  the 
assurance  given  or  no?"    Now,  of  course,  the  "object"  of  an  in- 
quiry or  judgment — i.e.,  of  the  raising  of  the  inquiry  or  the  mak- 
ing of  the  judgment — in  this  sense  of  the  term  is  undeniably  always 
present  or  future.     My  object,  the  fulfilment  of  my  intention,  in 
doing  anything  is  necessarily  synchronous  with  or  subsequent  to 
the  doing.     But  the  illicitness  of  the  substitution  of  this  sense  of 
"object"  for  the  former  needs  no  pointing  out.     Yet  it  is  solely 
by  means  of  this  unconscious  pun  that  Mr.  Dewey  gives  even  a 
semblance  of  plausibility  to  his  conclusion  that  "the  object  of  a 
judgment  is  always  prospective." 

When  we  revert  to  his  original,  and  only  pertinent,  definition  of 
object — "the  true  object  of  a  judgment  about  a  past  event  [must] 
be  a  past-event-having-a-connection-into-the-present-and-f uture ' ' T 
— it  becomes  evident  that  it  is  not  only  arbitrary  but  absurd  to 
single  out  from  that  total  "true  object"  of  the  judgment  one  part, 
the  present  and  future  part,  and  apply  to  it  exclusively  the  eulogis- 
tic descriptions  of  "the  object  or  genuine  meaning  of  the  judg- 

f  B.  M.  D.,  p.  ail. 


510  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ment,"  "the  actual  thing  meant."  The  absurdity,  of  course,  con- 
sists in  the  fact  that,  if  any  part  were  to  be  singled  out  for  such 
preferential  treatment,  it  would  be  precisely  the  part  to  which  Mr. 
Dewey,  in  his  final  conclusion,  refuses  recognition;  as  his  own  lan- 
guage shows,  the  judgment  is,  after  all,  "a  judgment  about  a  past 
event."  In  other  words,  the  present  and  future  facts  included  in 
what  he  regards  as  the  total  object  of  such  a  judgment  are  ad- 
mittedly logically  instrumental  to  a  knowledge  of  the  past  fact. 
True,  the  past  fact,  once  known,  may  in  a  subsequent  moment,  when 
reflection  is  directed  to  other  issues,  serve  as  the  means  of  proof  of 
something  else.  But  to  let  this  obscure  the  respective  logical  roles 
of  past  fact  and  present  and  future  facts  in  the  original,  actually 
retrospective,  inquiry  is  to  fall  into  the  fallacy  against  which  Mr. 
Dewey  himself  has  warned  us — that  of  failing  "properly  to  place 
the  distinctions  and  relations  which  figure  in  logical  theories  in  their 
temporal  context,"  of  "transferring  the  traits  of  the  subject-matter 
of  one  phase  to  that  of  another,  with  a  confusing  outcome. ' ' 8  Hav- 
ing arrived  at  the  retrospective  conclusion  that  A  killed  B,  a  court 
may  then  proceed  to  the  prospective  conclusion  that  A  ought  to  be 
hanged.  Doubtless — if  Mr.  Dewey  insists  on  his  pun — the  court's 
"object"  in  the  former  inquiry  was  to  determine  whether  or  not  A 
shall  be  hanged.  But  this  does  not  alter  the  fact  that  during  the 
trial  the  court's  function  consists  in  looking  backward,  and  that  the 
distinction  between  the  verdict,  which  is  mainly  the  business  of  one 
ret  of  men,  and  the  sentence,  which  is  usually  the  business  of  an- 
other man,  is  that  the  former  constitutes  an  assertion  about  what 
has  happened  and  the  latter  implies  an  assertion — in  American 
courts,  of  a  rather  low  order  of  probability — about  what  is  going 
to  happen.  If,  indeed,  pragmatist  writers  could  only  be  persuaded 
to  master  the  distinction  between  a  verdict  and  a  sentence,  they 
might  discover  why  it  is  that  their  critics  find  in  their  writings  a 
constant  and  baffling  confusion  of  temporal  categories. 

Let  me  now  briefly  recapitulate.  Mr.  Dewey 's  attempt  to  justify 
the  thesis  that  in  judgments  about  the  past  "the  actual  thing  meant, 
the  object  of  judgment,  is  prospective, ' '  consists  of  two  arguments : 
(a)  He  observes  that  the  "true,"  i.e.,  the  total,  object  of  any  ret- 
rospective judgment,  if  regarded  as  verifiable,  includes  present 
and  future  facts  which  are  the  means  of  its  verification.  This  is 
true  but  irrelevant.  The  object  of  such  a  judgment  also  includes 
past  facts;  these  do  not  lose  their  pastness  by  their  "connection 
with  the  present";  and  it  is  with  them  that  the  issue  raised  in  my 
paper  had  to  do.  (6)  His  other  argument  resolves  itself  into  the 

•  Essays  in  Experimental  Logic,  p.  1 ;  cited  in  E.  C.  S.,  p.  78. 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE  511 

substitution  of  one  sense  of  the  expression  "object  of  a  judgment" 
for  another  sense — namely,  of  the  sense  "fulfilment  of  the  inten- 
tion which  prompted  the  making  of  the  judgment"  for  the  sense 
"thing  or  event  logically  referred  to  by  the  judgment."  The  proof 
of  the  " prospectiveness "  of  the  judgment's  reference  is  based  upon 
the  former  meaning,  but  the  conclusion  is  illicitly  transferred  to  the 
latter.  Both  arguments  thus  fall  to  the  ground.  Yesterday,  qua 
yesterday,  still  remains  irreducibly  external  to  to-day,  existentially 
transcendent  of  all  the  present  thinkings  and  knowings  which  have 
to  do  with  it  and  all  the  present,  immediately  experienced  data 
which  give  circumstantial  evidence  concerning  it.  Mr.  Dewey, 
therefore,  has  in  fact  done  nothing  to  "eliminate  the  machinery  of 
tanscendence  and  of  epistemological  dualism,"  or  to  show  (in  the 
sense  required  by  the  argument)  that  "we  are  never  obliged,  even 
in  judgments  about  the  remotest  geological  past,  to  get  outside 
events  capable  of  future  and  present  consideration."9 

3.  The  sentence  just  quoted,  however,  is  worth  dwelling  upon; 
for  it  excellently  illustrates  a  certain  elusiveness  of  import  which 
seems  to  me  highly  characteristic  of  the  entire  argument.  The 
reader  will  have  observed  that  everything,  in  the  interpretation  of 
the  sentence,  depends  upon  the  meaning  assigned  to  the  words 
"capable  of  future  and  present  consideration,"  and  that  these 
words  may  bear  either  of  two  meanings.  They  may  most  naturally 
be  taken  to  mean  "capable  of  being  thought  of  in  the  present  and 
future."  So  taken,  the  sentence  embodies  the  most  harmless  of 
truisms;  undeniably,  "even  in  judgments  about  the  remotest  ge- 
ological past,"  we  never  "get  outside  events"  which  may  be  ob- 
jects of  present  or  future  thought.  But  here  it  is  the  thought  and 
not  the  thought's  object  that  is  present  or  future;  and  therefore, 
so  taken,  the  sentence  has  no  pertinency  to  its  context.  It  is  by  no 
means  equivalent  to  the  proposition  with  which  it  seems  supposed 
to  be  synonymous,  viz.,  that  "the  actual  thing  meant,  the  object  of 
judgment,  is  prospective."  To  make  it  fit  the  context,  therefore, 
the  reader's  mind  is  likely  to  transfer  the  futurity  or  presentness 
mentioned  from  the  thought  to  the  object.  So  taken,  the  sentence 
becomes  pertinent  but  it  also  becomes  the  most  glaring  of  paradoxes. 
And  it  is,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  from  this  quick  and  delicate, — and, 
of  course,  unconscious — shifting  of  meanings  and  of  matters-re- 
f  erred-to,  that  the  argument  must  gain  whatever  interest  and  plausi- 
bility it  can  conceivably  possess,  for  Mr.  Dewey  or  anyone  else.  It 
is  the  paradoxical  sense  of  the  ambiguous  proposition  which  gives 
it  its  interest,  its  appearance  of  novelty  and  importance,  and  it  is 

9  B.  M.  D.,  p.  316. 


512  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

its  platitudinous  sense  which  gives  it  its  appearance  of  truth  and 
even  self-evidence;  and  either  end  of  the  thing,  or  both  in  rapid 
alternation,  may  be  turned  towards  the  bewildered  critic  of  prag- 
matism, as  the  exigencies  of  controversy  require.  It  is  just  such  an 
unwitting  shift  of  meanings  that  renders  in  some  degree  intelligible 
(certainly  nothing  else  can  do  so)  Mr.  Dewey's  insistence  that 
' '  there  is  nothing  forced  or  paradoxical ' '  about  his  principal  thesis. 
Taken  as  stated  and  in  the  natural  sense  of  its  terms,  the  proposi- 
tion that  the  "actual  thing  meant"  by  a  retrospective  judgment  is 
prospective,  is  as  evident  and  as  queer  a  paradox  as  philosopher 
ever  penned.  But  taken  with  certain  qualifications  which  are  some- 
times suggested — and  which  really  reverse  the  meaning — it  is  in- 
deed no  paradox,  but  a  commonplace.  The  qualified  meaning  of 
the  statement  seems  to  be  that  already  discussed,  namely,  that  among 
the  things  at  least  implicitly  "meant"  by  a  judgment  about  the 
past,  in  so  far  as  that  judgment  is  conceived  as  verifiable,  are  pres- 
ent and  prospective  data  of  experience.  But  for  this  simple  and 
unimpeachable  statement  is  speedily  substituted  language  which, 
by  the  usual  rules  of  English  speech,  should  signify  that  the  sole 
"actual  thing  meant"  in  such  a  judgment  is  something  present  or 
prospective.  And  here  again  the  truth  of  the  first  proposition 
throws  its  mantle  over  the  paradoxically  of  the  second,  while,  re- 
ciprocating the  service,  the  paradoxicality  of  the  second  gives  to 
the  truth  of  the  first  an  air  of  unfamiliarity,  of  deep  and  stirring 
revelation. 

And  in  this  lies,  I  think,  the  real  nub  of  the  difficulty  in  the 
present  discussion.  It  is,  I  am  convinced,  this  fashion  of  treating 
as  equivalent  and  interchangeable  the  two  meanings  of  an  ambigu- 
ous proposition  that  gives  the  pragmatist  the  illusion  of  having  dis- 
covered a  new  way  of  escape  from  old  dilemmas;  and  it  is  this,  he 
ought  at  any  rate  to  be  told,  which  makes  his  reasonings,  to  some, 
of  his  readers,  puzzling  and  elusive  to  the  last  degree.10  And  now 
that  the  point  has  been  made  explicit,  I  venture  to  hope  that  Mr. 
Dewey  will  face  the  distinction  indicated  and  will  tell  us  plainly 
which  of  these  two  very  different  things  he  means  to  assert:  (a) 
the  flagrant  paradox  that  the  only  "thing  meant,"  in  a  judgment 
about  the  events  of  yesterday,  is  future  or  ' '  prospective ' ' — ' '  a  blank 
denial  that  we  can  think  of  the  past,"  as  a  philosophical  corre- 
spondent of  mine  puts  his  understanding  of  Mr.  Dewey's  meaning; 
or  (&)  the  familiar  commonplace  that  we  form  judgments  which 
relate  to  actual  past  events,  but  that  these  judgments  constitute 

10  The  play  upon  the  moaning  of  ' '  object, ' '  already  noted,  is  another  case  in 
point. 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE  513 

verifiable  knowledge  only  in  so  far  as  the  past  events  are  causally 
connected  with  present  or  future  existents  which  can  serve  as 
means  of  verification,  and  that  our  motive  in  judging  is  always 
some  present  interest.  The  choice  of  either  alternative  would  com- 
pel Mr.  Dewey  to  abandon  one  part  or  another  of  the  complex  of 
propositions  making  up  his  form  of  pragmatism.  If  he  elects  the 
first,  he  will  thereby  deny  such  judicious  observations  as  he  himself 
has  often  made,  to  the  effect  that  "detached  and  impartial  study 
of  the  past  is  the  only  alternative  to  luck  in  assuring  success  to 
passion";  and,  in  general,  will  repudiate  not  merely  a  primary 
conviction  .of  common  sense,  but  a  necessary  presupposition  of  the 
method  of  the  empirical  sciences.  If  he  elects  the  second  meaning 
of  his  equivocal  thesis,  he  is — as  has  already  been  sufficiently 
shown — then  faced  with  the  admitted  existential  externality  of  the 
past  object — or,  if  he  prefers  the  phrasing,  the  past  part  of  the  ob- 
ject— of  the  judgment.  The  case  for  epistemological  dualism  based 
upon  the  actual  pastness  of  the  object,  or  an  object,  of  the  retro- 
spective judgment  would  therefore  remain  unshaken.  And,  it  must 
be  added,  even  if  the  more  extreme  version  of  his  contention  about 
these  judgments  were  made  out,  the  main  issue  concerning  tran- 
scendence would  not  be  vitally  affected;  for  a  "prospective"  ob- 
ject is  as  manifestly  transcendent  as  a  past  object.  In  short,  all 
that  Mr.  Dewey  even  attempts  to  do  is  to  substitute  one  mode  of 
transcendence  for  another. 

4.  Mr.  Dewey  concludes  his  first  paper  with  a  counter-attack, 
charging  me,  and  apparently  critical  realists  generally,  with  a 
' '  subjectivism ' '  "  from  which  he  represents  his  own  version,  though 
not  all  versions,  of  pragmatism  as  free.  The  subjectivism  alleged 
consists  in  the  view  that,  since  our  retrospective  judgments  mean 
but  do  not  actually  include  and  possess  the  past,  belief  in  their 
validity,  in  the  existence  of  the  past  to  which  they  refer,  involves 
an  element  of  alogical  faith,  explicit  or  implicit.  At  any  given 
moment  of  reflection  the  testimony  of  his  memory  is  the  only  evi- 
dence any  man  possesses  as  to  any  empirical  fact  whatever,  beyond 
the  immediately  present  sense-data;  but  the  testimony  of  memory 
can  not  itself  be  empirically  verified.  My  entire  store  of  recollec- 

11  It  is  unnecessary  to  comment  at  length  on  Mr.  Dewey 's  assertion  that  my 
view — and  any  dualistie  or  monistic  realism — implies  that  "isolated,  self-com- 
plete things  are  truly  objects  of  knowledge."  "Isolated"  past  events  are,  in 
the  sense  that  they  are  external  to  the  present;  isolated  they  are  not,  and  axe 
not  by  the  realist  held  to  be,  in  any  sense  which  denies  their  "connection  with 
past  and  future. ' '  Mr.  Dewey  is  here  (p.  315,  foot)  attacking  a  man  of  straw, 
the  misdirection  of  his  attack  being  due  to  a  failure  to  discriminate  between 
logical  distinction  and  lack  of  causal  connection. 


514  JOURNAL  OF  FHILOSOI'II  Y 

tions  may  conceivably  bo  illusory;  that  they  are  not  can  not  be 
proved,  mid  belief  in  their  general  trustworthiness  is  therefore  an 
instinctive  and  practically  necessary  assumption  which  outruns 
proof.  This  I  had  always  supposed  to  be  a  universally  accepted, 
though  an  important,  truism.  But  Mr.  Dcwey  rejects  it.  Never 
will  the  true  pragmatist  "isolate  the  needs  or  propensities  of  the 
agent  and  regard  them  as  grounds  of  belief  in  the  validity  of  mean- 
ing." As  against  the  realist's  weak  yielding  to  "instinctive  pro- 
pensities," the  pragmatist  insists  austerely  upon  "logical  verifica- 
tion." 

Now  if  Mr.  Dewey  has  really  discovered  a  way  out  of  this  an- 
cient impasse  of  thought,  has  found  a  strictly  "logical"  means  of 
verification  of  the  reality  of  yesterday  and  the  validity  of  retrospec- 
tion as  such,  he  has,  assuredly,  made  a  most  momentous  contribu- 
tion to  philosophy.  But  the  discovery,  if  made,  is  not  disclosed  in 
his  paper.  None  of  the  three  considerations  which  he  adduces  prove 
the  possibility  of  any  such  verification,  (a)  He  apparently  thinks 
that  those  who  deny  the  possibility  of  a  strict  verification  of  the 
general  belief  in  a  real  past  and  of  the  general  trustworthiness  of 
memory,  as  it  exists  from  moment  to  moment,-  must  dispense  with 
logic  altogether  and  follow  merely  their  "instinctive  propensities" 
in  deciding  what  particular  judgments  about  the  past  they  will  be- 
lieve and  what  reject.  But  this  by  no  means  follows.  The  structure 
of  any  logical  system  of  empirical  beliefs  is  obvious  enough.  We 
first  postulate,  or  implicitly  assume,  that  there  was  a  past  and  that 
our  present  memories  constitute  a  source  of  knowledge  concerning 
it,  except  in  so  far  as  they  are  subject  to  certain  conflicts  inter  se. 
We  then  find  these  memories  exhibiting  certain  prevailing  uniformi- 
ties of  sequence  and  coexistence  among  the  things  remembered; 
from  these  we  derive  our  conception  of  a  regular  order  of  nature; 
and  finally  we  reject  as  spurious  any  memory-content  which  con- 
flicts with  this  order,  and  as  doubtful  any  which  our  present  memo- 
ries of  the  fortunes  of  former  rememberings  render  suspect.  But 
the  necessity  for  that  initial  postulation  the  pragmatist  can  as 
little  escape  as  any  other  man  who  will  take  the  trouble  to  reflect 
at  all  upon  the  logical  grounds  of  his  beliefs.  (&)  Mr.  D<- 
however,  seems  to  suppose  that  he  has  escaped  it  by  his  "account  of 
knowledge  involving  past  events" — which  presumably  refers  again 
to  the  proposition  that  "the  actual  thing  meant"  in  such  knowl- 
edge is  "prospective."  But  this  proposition  must,  once  more,  be 
taken  either  in  its  literal  and  paradoxical,  or  in  its  qualified  and 
truistic  sense.  In  the  former,  it  signifies  that  we  never  mean,  and 
therefore  never  have  as  objects  of  our  knowledge,  any  past  events 


DR.  MCTAGGART  AND  CAUSALITY  515 

whatever.  Such  a  thesis  is  hardly  favorable  to  the  view  that  knowl- 
edge of  the  past  is  "logically  verifiable."  In  the  qualified  sense, 
the  proposition,  as  we  have  seen,  means  that  we  do  actually  know 
the  past,  with  the  aid  of  present  memory-images  and  sense-data. 
But  how  the  present  existences  constitute  a  true  "logical  verifica- 
tion" of  past  existences,  the  proposition  does  not  explain,  (c) 
Finally,  Mr.  Dewey  tells  us,  in  familiar  pragmatistic  language,  that 
a  belief  about  the  past  is  "verified  or  condemned  by  its  conse- 
quences." This,  however,  is  another  example  of  the  error  from 
which  the  pragmatist,  of  all  men,  should  be  most  free — the  con- 
fusion of  the  traits  of  one  temporal  phase  of  experience  with  those 
of  another.  When  the  consequences  of  a  prior  belief  arrive,  that  be- 
lief is  already  "past  and  gone  forever";  and  how,  at  the  later 
moment,  we  can — except  by  means  of  a  faith  in  memory — know 
even  that  there  was  a  prior  belief  of  which  these  are  the  conse- 
quences, Mr.  Dewey  does  nothing  to  make  clear. 

Considered  as  historical  phenomena,  most  of  the  aspects  of  Pro- 
fessor Dewey 's  view  about  judgments  of  the  past  which  I  have  here 
criticized  seem  to  me  to  be  simply  manifestations  of  the  working 
of  the  old  leaven  of  epistemological  idealism,  and  of  the  wrong  sort 
of  intellectualism,  of  which  pragmatism  has  not  yet  purged  itself — 
expressions  of  an  obscure  feeling  that  nothing  ought  to  be  treated 
as  "known"  which  is  not  immediately  given,  actually  present, 
totally  verified  on  the  spot.  For  the  critical  realist,  on  the  con- 
trary, all  our  knowledge  (beyond  bare  sensory  content)  is  a  kind 
of  foreign  commerce,  a  trafficking  with  lands  in  which  the  traffickers 
do  not  live,  but  from  which  they  may  continually  bring  home  good 
store  of  merchandise  to  enrich  the  here-and-now.  And  like  all  such 
traffic,  it  requires  first  of  all  a  certain  venture  of  belief,  instinctive 
with  most  men,  deliberate  and  self-conscious  with  those  who  re- 
flect. 

ARTHUR  0.  LOVEJOY. 
JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY. 


DR.  McTAGGART  AND  CAUSALITY 

MANY  different  persons  compose  the  public,  which  thus  contains 
a  multitude  of  minds.  Sociologists  dispute  with  one  another 
over  the  existence  of  a  single  public  mind  that  combines  this  multi- 
tude, into  one.  It  is  convenient  to  assume,  for  some  purposes,  this 
unitary  combination  of  many  individual  minds,  as  any  particular 
mind  is  composed  of  many  thoughts.  It  is  convenient  when  so  many 


516  JOURNAL  OF  PH1L08OPH  Y 

members  of  the  multitude  think  alike  that  one  common  mind  seems 
to  have  one  thought.  There  are  such  occasions  and  the  public  esti- 
mate of  Dr.  McTaggart 's  The  Nature  of  Existence  would  very 
probably  be  one  of  them.  Dr.  McTaggart  has  himself  supplied  a 
sentence  to  express  this  public  estimate.  Most  people,  perhaps  even 
including  many  professional  philosophers,  would  only  see  in  The 
Nature  of  Existence  an  elaborate  and  unnecessary  amplification 
of  the  sentence  on  page  136  which  reads:  "But  things  which  are 
unimportant  are  none  the  less  real."  The  public  adoption  of  this 
sentence  to  characterize  the  book  would  not  adopt  the  motive  which 
prompted  it.  Dr.  McTaggart 's  sympathies  center  on  the  word 
"real,"  but  the  public  emphasis  would  fall  on  the  word  "unim- 
portant." The  unanimous  public  mind  would  probably  admit,  with- 
out troubling  to  inquire  further,  the  possible  truth  of  Dr.  McTag- 
gart's  opinions,  and  then  decline  to  discuss  them.  The  writer  himself 
probably  only  expects  to  appeal  to  a  few  minds  who  will  study  the 
problem  of  existence  without  requiring  an  immediate  connection 
with  the  interests  of  practical  life.  He  does  hope  to  derive  some 
insight  into  questions  of  practical  interest  from  his  discussion  of 
the  general  nature  of  the  existent  (p.  51),  but  he  probably  expects 
the  public  mind  to  prefer  a  more  immediate  study  of  the  practical 
to  such  a  long  metaphysical  detour. 

The  most  practically  minded  person  may  feel  the  fascination  of 
the  principle  stated  on  page  87 :"  when  any  substance  changes,  all 
substances  must  change."  The  pen  of  the  astronomer,  it  has  been 
said,  as  it  records  or  calculates  the  motions  of  the  planets,  alters 
these  motions  by  its  own  movements.  The  imperceptible  effect  on 
a  giant  planet  of  the  insignificant  pen  appeals  to  imagination  as 
a  revelation  of  the  sensitiveness  of  the  universe  to  its  most  micro- 
scopic occurrences.  It  appeals  also  to  the  innate  human  desire  to 
exert  control  by  suggesting  that  the  slightest  human  action  spreads 
its  influence  through  society.  But  the  imaginative  appeal  of  theo- 
retically existent  but  imperceptible  and  irrelevant  influences  can  not 
stay  the  vehement  human  hunt  after  effects  more  patent,  more  im- 
pressive and  more  palpably  enduring.  The  susceptibilities  of  the 
universe  of  substances  to  the  changes  in  one  of  them,  as  stated  by 
Dr.  McTaggart,  have  too  little  dramatic  flavor  to  inspire  a  reformer. 
There  is  a  suggestion  of  important  possibilities  if  it  is  tme  that 
Brown's  body  changes  when  Smith,  after  being  thinner  than  Brown, 
becomes  fatter  than  he.  If  Smith  can  change  Brown's  body  by  a 
change  in  his  own  body  perhaps  he  can  affect  Brown's  political 
opinions  by  altering  his  own :  a  vista  of  entrancing  possibility  is 
promptly  opened.  Dr.  McTaggart,  however,  is  thinking  of  change 


DR.  MCTAGGART  AND  CAUSALITY  517 

in  a  very  practically  unimportant  sense,  though  it  is  very  real. 
When  Smith  was  thinner  than  Brown,  Brown's  body  was  related 
to  Smith's  body  by  being  fatter.  This  relationship  generated  in 
Brown's  body  the  quality  of  being  fatter  than  Smith's.  When 
Smith  becomes  the  fatter  of  the  two  Brown's  body  alters  its  quality 
of  being  fatter  than  Smith's  to  the  quality  of  being  thinner.  The 
ardent  reformer  might  reflect,  as  he  is  faced  with  this  illustration 
of  universal  interaction,  on  his  stupidity  in  reading  past  page  7. 
''On  the  other  hand,"  Dr.  McTaggart  there  remarks  in  a  footnote, 
"the  possibility  that  it  might  be  raining  now,  when  in  point  of  fact 
it  is  not  raining,  has  no  practical  interest  for  me."  The  first  seven 
pages  should  have  shown  to  anybody,  the  reflecting  reformer  might 
well  think,  that  the  whole  book  was  devoted  to  precisely  such  prac- 
tically unimportant  possibilities. 

If  the  practically  minded  representative  of  the  public  reads 
paragraphs  30  to  33  he  will  probably  think  that  the  study  of  "the 
characteristics  which  belong  to  all  that  exists,  or  again,  which  belong 
to  Existence  as  a  whole"  (p.  3)  promotes  peculiarity  of  thought  as 
well  as  devotion  to  practically  unimportant  possibilities.  Any  two 
things,  selected  from  the  vast  store  of  the  universe,  have,  he  learns, 
the  same  number  of  characteristics,  and  he  may  be  too  contemp- 
tuous of  the  proof  to  relish  its  deftness.  A  poker  is  hard  and  long 
and  shining  and,  it  may  be  supposed,  to  the  north  of  London.  An 
idea  in  a  mind  has  corresponding  qualities — but  it  has  the  quality 
of  being  not-hard,  of  being  not-long,  of  being  not-shining  and  is, 
presumably,  not  to  the  north  of  London.  If  the  idea  is  vivid  the 
poker  has  a  corresponding  quality  of  being  not-vivid  and  so,  by 
ascribing  to  everything  every  relation  or  quality,  either  positively 
or  negatively,  any  single  thing  has  precisely  the  same  number  of 
characteristics  as  any  other.  Since  a  shiny  poker  is  not  only  more 
shining  than  an  unpolished  one  but  also  has  the  quality  of  possess- 
ing a  total  group  of  qualities  which,  because  it  includes  shininess, 
is  different  from  the  group  of  qualities  possessed  by  the  dull  poker, 
since  this  development  of  qualities  and  relations  could  be  indefinitely 
extended  and  since  a  similar  unending  development  of  qualities  and 
relations  could  proceed  from  any  one  point  of  comparison  between 
the  poker  and  any  other  existent  thing  the  poker  has  an  infinity 
of  characteristics — qualities  and  relations.  The  hypothetical  single 
public  mind,  which  can  be  conveniently  substituted  for  many  gasp- 
ing individuals,  will  probably  marvel  at  the  peculiar  preference  of 
the  metaphysician  for  researches  which  diffuse  themselves  over  un- 
important suppositions  and  very  dubious  speculations. 

Our  natural  practical  instincts  incline  us  to  a  sharp  distinction 
between  mere  mechanical  aggregates,  like  a  heap  of  stones,  and 


518  JOURNAL  OF  FHILOSOI'II  V 

organic  unities,  like  a  plant  or  a  tiger  or  a  human  society.  When  a 
handful  of  stones  is  removed  from  the  heap  it  becomes  smaller  with- 
out appearing  to  be  further  sensitive  to  the  change  in  its  parts. 
The  whole  tiger  is  more  sensitive  to  the  removal  of  his  tail  and  the 
loss  of  its  chief  sends  an  emotion  through  the  whole  of  a 
human  group.  We  think  naturally  of  tigers  and  societies  as 
"genuine  wholes  in  which  no  part  nor  characteristic  is  indif- 
ferent to  any  other."  A  triangle,  Professor  Bosanquet  adds 
to  this  definition  of  "a  genuine  whole,"  is  imperfectly  genuine 
in  this  sense  because  there  is  some  indifference:  its  angles 
have  the  same  sizes,  however  big  or  small  it  may  be,  if  it 
keeps  the  same  shape  (Implication  and  Linear  Inference,  p.  7). 
For  non-metaphysical  wisdom  the  heap  of  stones  is  even  less  sensitive 
to  its  parts  and  less  genuinely  a  whole  than  the  triangle.  If  we 
accept  hints  from  Dr.  McTaggart  we  observe  a  greater  sensitiveness 
in  the  heap  to  its  parts.  If  it  has  as  many  stones  as  a  neighboring 
heap  before  it  loses  a  handful,  it  alters  its  quality  of  being  equal 
to  its  neighbor  to  the  quality  of  being  less.  It  may  become  less 
than  many  other  heaps  which  were  previously  larger  than  itself  and 
each  new  relation  involves  a  new  quality  in  the  heap.  Dr.  McTag- 
part  would  probably  suggest  to  Professor  Bosanquet  that  the  angles 
of  a  large  triangle  do  differ  from  the  angles  of  a  triangle  which 
is  smaller  and  has  the  same  shape.  The  angles  in  the  larger  tri- 
angle are  angles  which  have  the  quality  of  being  related  to  a  triangle 
which  is  larger  than  the  smaller  triangle,  and  the  angles  in  the 
smaller  triangle,  since  they  are  related  to  a  triangle  which  is  smaller 
than  the  larger  triangle,  have  a  different  quality  from  the  angles  of 
the  latter.  If  Dr.  McTaggart  is  right  then  "all  wholes  are  really 
organic  unities"  because  "since  the  whole  as  a  unity  is  what  it  is, 
the  parts  must  be  what  they  are"  (The  Nature  of  Existence,  p.  161). 
These  Hegelian  refinements  touch  a  sympathetic  chord  through  the 
practical  crust  on  our  minds.  Dr.  McTaggart  gets  the  whole  uni- 
verse into  an  organic  unity  which  is  sensitive  to  all  changes  in  its 
parts.  He  seems  to  turn  our  ears  to  Blake  as  he  says  "For  not 
one  sparrow  can  suffer,  and  the  whole  universe  not  suffer  also" 
(Jerusalem,  Ch.  1,  XXV,  8). 

There  is  more  appeal  in  Blake's  sparrow  than  in  Dr.  McTaggart 's 
more  bloodless  multitude  of  abstract  qualities  and  relations.  Dr. 
McTaggart  realizes  that  suffering  appeals  more  to  our  sense  of 
life  than  does  the  cold  recognition  that  the  pain  of  a  sparrow  alters 
in  a  regardless  passer-by  the  quality  of  being  near  a  happy  sparrow 
to  the  quality  of  being  near  a  sparrow  which  suffers.  He  would 
doubtless  insist  on  the  equal  reality  of  both  forms  of  sensitiveness 


DR.  MCTAGGART  AND  CAUSALITY  519 

in  the  universal  whole  without  denying  the  greater  importance  for 
practical  life  of  sympathy  with  suffering.  He  insists  that  our 
customary  standards  of  value  determine  our  customary  division  of 
things  into  biological  organisms  and  beautiful  objects,  which  are 
organic  unities,  and  into  more  mechanical  aggregates  which  are  not. 
The  decrease  in  size  of  a  stony  heap  is  only  important  for  special 
purposes ;  slight  changes  in  living  or  beautiful  things  produce  differ- 
ences which  affect  our  sense  of  value  (p.  161).  His  deduction  from 
a  survey  of  the  less  impressive,  and  apparently  very  unimportant, 
modes  of  sensitiveness  in  wholes  to  changes  in  their  parts,  that  all 
wholes  are  organic  unities,  is  a  reminder  of  the  disturbance  which 
practical  common  sense  notions  may  exert  on  the  effort  to  under- 
stand the  real  nature  of  the  universe. 

This  lesson  may  be  drawn  from  The  Nature  of  Existence  if  all 
else  is  rejected.     The  way  of  philosophical  understanding  opens  out 
of  the  way  of  life  because  before  becoming  philosophers  we  must 
first  live.    But  it  is  not  merely  its  continuation.    The  impression  of 
hopeless  irrelevance  first  made  upon  our  minds  by  The  Nature  of 
Existence  is  the  response  of  men  who  spontaneously  estimate  every- 
thing by  its  direct  bearing  on  their  lives  to  a  problem  which  in- 
cludes them  as  items  in  a  vaster,  universal  whole.     The  notions  of 
relevance  and  irrelevance  imposed  upon  us  by  the  exigencies  of 
life,  which  only  demand  from  us  knowledge  adequate  for  our  pri- 
mary purposes,  may  have  to  give  way  before  the  wider  demands 
of  knowledge.     "We  do  not,  in  any  ordinary  relevant  sense,  alter 
objects  by  perceiving  them.    An  apple  retains  the  same  shape,  color 
or  taste  whether  it  is  or  is  not  being  looked  at.     There  are  differ- 
ences, however,  between  the  perceived  and  the  unperceived  apple 
which  are  usually  ignored  because  they  are  practically  irrelevant. 
When  A  looks  at  the  apple  it  is  cognitively  related  to  him  and  has 
the   quality  of  being  perceived.     It   sheds  this  relation   and  the 
quality  generated  from  it  when  A  turns  away  to  look  at  something 
else.     Its  characteristics  do  not  diminish,  on  Dr.  McTaggart's  doc- 
trine, because  it  is  now  unperceived  by  A  and  has  a  corresponding 
negative  quality.     An  exhibitor  of  pictures  need  not  sharpen  his 
apprehension  of  their  qualities  and  relations  by  studying  The  Na- 
ture of  Existence.    Neither  he  nor  his  patrons  will  affect  his  paint- 
ings by  merely  looking  at  them  in  any  way  relevant  to  esthetic  ap- 
preciation :  their  colors  will  not  fade  nor  any  other  of  their  physical 
qualities  be  altered  by  simple  inspection.     It  is  less  certain  that 
the  epistemologist  can  say  dogmatically:  "Knowing  is  never  making. 
It  is  just  knowing."     (Laird,  A  Study  in  Realism,  p.  35.)     Since 
epistemolcgy  is  wider  than  exhibiting  pictures  it  may  be  its  duty  to 


JOURNAL  OF  PHlLOSOl'll  Y 

remember  that  a  painting  is  never  the  same  under  inspection  as  it 
:>  in  the  dark.  The  contemplating  mind  appears  to  common  sense 
to  select  its  object  from  a  world  of  being  which  is  distinct  from,  and, 
in  this  sense,  independent  of  itself  (Alexander,  Space,  Time  and 
Deity,  i,  15).  If  the  process  of  selection  determines  in  the  object 
the  quality  of  being  thus  selected,  the  quality  of  being  perceived 
and  many  other  qualities  determined  by  these  two,  the  serenity  of 
this  conclusion  is  disturbed.  The  impression  of  hopeless  irrelevance 
begins  to  pass  into  an  impression  of  ultimate  and  philosophically 
significant  relevancy.  The  geometer  can  often  come  down  success- 
fully upon  a  problem  relating  to  lines  and  triangles  in  two  dimen- 
sions by  considering  the  analogous  problem  in  three  dimensions. 
Perhaps  the  abstract  qualities  and  relations  discussed  by  Dr.  McTag- 
gart  may  serve  the  philosopher  as  the  higher  dimension  serves  the 
geometer.  He  may  be  able  to  descend  successfully  from  the  study 
of  the  characters  of  all  existents,  or  of  existence  as  a  whole,  irrele- 
vant and  hopelessly  abstract  as  they  may  at  first  appear,  upon 
problems  which  have  been  discussed  on  the  tacit  assumption  of 
their  irrelevance. 

By  such  a  descent  organic  unities  may  cease  to  be  regarded  as 
intruders  into  an  unorganized  world.  The  epistemologist  who  sup- 
poses his  perceived  object  to  be  unaffected  by  his  perceptions  may, 
by  making  his  survey  more  comprehensive,  discover  more  universal 
interaction  than  his  theories  contemplate.  The  past  is  not  fixed  if 
the  coronation  of  Queen  Victoria  ceased  to  be  the  last  British  coro- 
nation in  1903.  (The  Nature  of  Existence,  p.  87.)  Will  a  per- 
sistent exploration  of  the  ultimate  characteristics  which  belong  to 
existence  or  existents  as  a  whole  as  such  permit  a  successful  descent 
upon  the  vexed  question  of  causation?  Will  "cause"  and  "effect" 
obviously  disappear  or  be  obviously  confirmed  under  Dr.  Mc- 
Taggart's  dialectic?  Dr.  McTaggart  has  no  doubts  and  firmly 
restores  the  concept  of  causality  uhich  has  been  dismissed  by  the 
anti-causationists  of  the  day.  The  concept  has  been  a  little  distorted, 
though  not  seriously  draggled,  during  its  passage  into  exile  and 
back,  but  it  does  return. 

Mr.  Bertrand  Russell  has  a  favorite  device  for  discrediting  the 
causal  relation.  He  delights  in  interrupting  causal  sequences  by 
interventions:  if  a  man  is  shot  immediately  after  taking  a  fatal  dose 
of  arsenic  the  dose  is  deprived  of  its  causal  effect  (The  Analysis  of 
Mind,  p.  94).  This  compels  a  shortening  of  the  time-interval  be- 
tween cause  and  effect  to  avoid  the  intrusion  of  such  interventions 
which  ultimately  coalesces  them  into  indistinguishableness.  This 
cup-and-mouth  argument  strikes  hard  at  the  inevitableness  of  con- 


DR.  MCTAGGART  AND  CAUSALITY  521 

nection  which  the  causal  relation  implies.  Science  can  get  no  nearer 
to  the  traditional  causal  law  than  to  say,  "A  is  usually  followed  by 
B"  (p.  96).  Mr.  Russell  selects  favorable  ground  for  this  crusade 
against  causality.  "I  put  my  penny  in  the  slot,  but  before  I  can 
draw  out  my  ticket  there  is  an  earthquake  which  upsets  the  machine 
and  my  calculations."  Rigid  determinations  will  be  less  discernible 
in  complex  phenomena  and  amid  the  stir  and  fuss  of  the  varied 
world  of  events  and  things  it  is  necessary  that  "to  be  sure  of  the 
expected  effect  we  must  know  that  there  is  nothing  in  the  environ- 
ment to  interfere  with  it. ' '  They  will  be  less  discernible  also  because 
''as  soon  as  we  include  the  environment,  the  probability  of  repeti- 
tion is  diminished,  until  at  last,  when  the  whole  environment  is  in- 
cluded, the  probability  of  repetition  becomes  almost  nil"  (Mysticism 
and  Logic,  p.  187).  Repetition  is  not  necessary  to  rigid  determina- 
tions, though,  if  it  occurs,  it  assists  in  their  recognition.  Obviously, 
the  examination  of  complex  phenomena  favors  the  application  of  the 
cup-and-mouth  argument  because  rigid  determinations  will  neither 
be  prominent  in  repetitions  nor  lie  nakedly  in  the  complexities  ex- 
amined. 

The  differential  equations  which  supersede  spurious  causal  laws 
in  advanced  sciences  (p.  194)  conceal  causality  by  summarization. 
Buckle  was  greatly  impressed  by  the  statistical  constancies  dis- 
covered by  Queletet.  He  mentions,  among  others,  the  constant  an- 
nual number  of  unaddressed  letters  (History  of  Civilization  in 
England,  i,  32).  Supposing,  to  fix  ideas,  that  for  every  10,000 
people  in  the  British  Isles  one  letter  is  posted  every  year  without 
an  address,  the  equation  unaddressed  letters  X  10,000  =  population 
represents  this  statistical  constancy.  This  simple  equation,  assum- 
ing it  to  be  more  stringently  true  than  in  reality,  illustrates  the 
mathematical  ignoring  of  causes.  The  statistician  anticipates  the 
number  of  unaddressed  letters  during  any  year  by  dividing  the 
number  representing  the  population  by  10,000.  The  mathematical 
result,  as  such,  is  independent  of  causes,  but  it  is  only  possible  be- 
cause causes  operate.  There  is  a  cause  for  the  posting  of  each  un- 
addressed letter :  absence  of  mind  in  some  instances,  hurry  in  others 
and  many  more  besides.  The  mathematical  summary  drops  the 
causes  out,  but  if  they  were  not  it  would  not  be.  The  choice  of 
the  differential  equation  to  confute  the  pro-causationists  is  even  more 
effective  than  the  choice  of  complicated  phenomena  to  conceal  causal 
connections.  "With  the  latter  the  cup-and-mouth  argument  is  needed, 
but  is  effective  because  it  is  difficult  to  uncover  connections  in  their 
nakedness.  But  it  is  not  needed  with  the  former  because  differen- 
tial, or  other,  equations  bury  causal  connections  quite  out  of  sight 


522  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

in  a  summary.  Bertrand  Russell  crusades  very  successfully  on  his 
chosen  ground  but  will  his  conclusion  that  "The  Law  of  Causality 
.  .  .  like  much  that  passes  muster  among  philosophers,  is  a  relic 
of  a  bygone  age,  surviving,  like  the  monarchy,  only  because  it  is 
erroneously  supposed  to  do  no  harm"  (Mysticism  and  Logic,  p.  180) 
survive  a  descent  upon  it  from  the  ultimate  characteristics  of  exist- 
ents  and  existence? 

Anything  which  has  a  quality  must  be  related  to  that  quality 
in  that  it  possesses  it.  (The  Nature  of  Existence,  p.  112.)  This 
change  of  ground  supplies  McTaggart  with  a  route  of  descent  into 
the  rigid  determinations  which  Russell  so  successfully  conceals.  He 
discovers  the  relation  of  intrinsic  determination  among  the  ultimate 
characteristics  of  existents.  "If  it  is  true  that,  whenever  something 
has  the  quality  X,  something  has  the  quality  Y,  this  involves  that, 
besides  the  relation  between  the  two  propositions  'something  has  the 
quality  X,'  and  'something  has  the  quality  Y.'  there  is  relation 
between  the  qualities  X  and  Y.  I  propose  to  call  this  relation  In- 
trinsic Determination"  (p.  111).  If  anything  is  blue  it  is  spatial 
(p.  Ill) ;  if  a  certain  man  is  a  husband,  a  certain  woman  must  be 
a  wife  (p.  112) ;  if  anything  stands  in  a  relation  it  has  the  quality 
of  being  a  term  in  that  relation  (p.  112).  There  are  inevitable 
or  rigid  connections  which  are  proof  against  all  interventions  and 
can  not  be  summarized  away  in  a  formula  or  by  a  differential  equa- 
tion. Two  qualities  may  intrinsically  determine  one  another  di- 
rectly or  they  may  determine  one  another  more  indirectly.  "The 
two  qualities  of  Snowdon,  being  a  mountain  and  being  M  feet  high, 
do  extrinsically  determine  one  another.  For  anything  -which  had 
not  the  quality  of  being  today  M  feet  high  would  not  be  the  sub- 
stance which  we  call  Snowdon"  (p.  115).  There  is  no  intrinsic 
determination  between  being  a  mountain  and  being  M  feet  high,  as 
there  is  between  being  a  mountain  and  spatiality,  because  a  moun- 
tain may  be  any  height  above  1,000  feet.  But  since  Snowdon  is 
M  feet  high  and  is  a  mountain  these  two  qualities  are  extrinsically 
co-determinate  because  of  their  connection  with  that  particular 
mountain.  "All  qualities  of  a  substance  extrinsically  determine  one 
another"  (p.  114)  :  if  a  quality  of  a  substance  changes,  its  nature 
changes,  and  each  other  of  its  qualities  becomes  a  member  of  a 
different  group,  though  the  difference  may  be  slight,  of  qualities. 
"All  oxistonts  are  thus  bound  together  in  one  system  of  extrinsic 
determination"  (p.  151),  but  the  relation  of  intrinsic  determination 
bears  more  directly  on  causality.  The  discussion  of  the  peculiar 
form  of  Intrinsic  Determination  which  is  defined  by  Dr.  MeTaercrart 
a*  determining  correspondence  (p.  214)  can  be  avoided  in  following 
the  descent  from  Intrinsic  Determination  into  causality. 


DR.  MCTAGGART  AND  CAUSALITY  523 

The  death  of  Charles  I  and  his  execution  seem  to  preclude  any 
intervention  that  could  separate  them  or  violate  their  Intrinsic  De- 
termination. The  execution  might  have  been  prevented,  and  pre- 
vented even  as  the  axe  descended,  but  when  his  head  was  severed, 
Charles  had  to  die.  We  are  very  close  to  a  discovery  of  causal 
connections,  for  the  execution  of  Charles  would  be  ordinarily  re- 
garded as  the  cause  of  his  death  and  as  inevitably  producing  it. 
Fifty  years  hence,  or  earlier,  surgery  may  intervene  successfully 
between  decapitation  and  death.  This  abstract  possibility,  which 
could  not  be  disproved,  saves  the  cup-and-mouth  argument  from 
defeat  at  this  point:  it  is  not  easily  defeated  on  its  own  ground. 
Meanwhile,  a  reasonable  argument  might  run,  in  our  particular  part 
of  the  universe  and  pending  a  possible  achievement  of  surgery :  be- 
heading determines  death  and  the  two  are  tied  together  as  cause 
and  effect. 

Intervention  between  antecedent  and  subsequent  is  more  ob- 
viously possible  between  drinking  alcohol  and  intoxication.  A 
draught  of  alcohol  normally  enough  to  result  in  drunkenness  may 
leave  a  drinker  who  is  abnormal  or  abnormally  situated  still  sober. 
Determination  can  be  approached  more  closely  by  reversing  the  order 
earlier-later  to  the  order  later-earlier  and  by  taking  the  qualities 
more  precisely  (p.  238).  Any  man  who  is  drunken  with  all  the 
characteristics  of  alcoholic  intoxication  must  have  taken  alco- 
hol: alcoholic  intoxication  intrinsically  determines  drinking  alco- 
hol in  sufficient  quantity.  This  inversion  of  the  direction  of 
determination  qualifies  the  ordinary  conception  of  causation 
which  contemplates  only  a  forwards  determination  of  effect"  by 
cause  without  a  backwards  determination  of  cause,  by  effect.  Causa- 
tion becomes  a  particular  instance  of  intrinsic  determination  where 
the  terms  are  temporally  distinguished — the  cause  being  merely 
the  earlier  and  the  effect  merely  the  later.  The  relative  positions  of 
the  cause  and  effect  in  time  alone  distinguish  causation  from  other 
instances  of  intrinsic  determination  (p.  227) — the  cause  exerts  no 
activity  on  the  effect  (p.  224).  Dr.  McTaggart  includes  in  the 
conception  of  causation  its  occurrence  as  a  relation  between  qualities, 
since  all  intrinsic  determination  is  between  qualities,  though  these 
qualities  include  relational  qualities  (pp.  220-221),  i.e..  qualities  of 
substances  which  arise  directly  out  of  their  relations.  This  version 
would  probably  not  satisfy  all  pro-causationists — not  Mercier  who 
thought  causes  entered  into  permanent  phenomena  to  disturb  their 
tranquillity,  as  events  (On  Causation  with  a  Chapter  on  Belief, 
Ch.  2),  and  not  Lossky,  for  whom  the  idea  of  causal  connection  im- 
plies one  event  actively  producing  another  (The  Intuitive  Basis  of 


524  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Knowledge,  Duddington's  trans,  p.  23).  Dr.  McTaggart  also  in- 
cludes in  the  conception  of  cause  the  involvement  of  general  laws 
(The  Nature  of  Existence,  p.  154). 

Causality  thus  reduces  to  a  temporal  distinction  in  Intrinsic 
Determination.  Dr.  McTaggart 's  restoration  of  the  concept  of  caus- 
ality has  obviously  involved  it  in  some  critical  reconstruction.  A 
tie  or  necessary  connection  is  left  between  cause  and  effect,  but  ef- 
ficacy or  agency  is  rejected. 

Alexander,  in  one  place,  describes  causation  as  "the  continuous 
connection  in  sequence  of  two  events  within  a  substance"  (Space, 
Time  and  Deity,  ii,  153).  This  apparent  acquiescence  in  the  ex- 
traction of  the  effective  element  from  the  causal  sequence  is  ap- 
parently contradicted  by  a  recognition  of  "the  influence  of  one 
thought  in  our  minds  over  another"  (ii,  152).  He  seems  to  avoid 
the  introduction  of  efficacy  into  physical  causation :  physical  causa- 
tion is  the  continuous  transition  of  one  physical  event  into  another 
(i,  97),  and  causality  is  a  relation  of  continuity  between  two  differ- 
ent motions  (i,  279).  When  he  adds  that  "our  power  is  an  instance 
of  causality,"  that  power  or  necessity  is  not  contained  in  the  con- 
ception of  causality  as  a  category  and  that  "our  awareness  of 
power  is  but  our  consciousness  of  the  causal  relation  between  our 
will  and  our  acts"  (i,  291)  he  seems  to  acquiesce  in  the  expulsion 
of  efficaciousness  from  causation.  "Self-initiation"  results  from 
the  addition  of  "the  consciousness  of  activity"  to  "simple  causality" 
(ii,  154),  minds  and  external  things,  as  compresent,  are  in  causal 
relation  (ii,  155)  :  he  thus  seems  in  sympathy  with  McTaggart 's  re- 
duction of  this  much  disputed  category  to  a  "  ...  modest  but  per- 
vasive category  of  causation"  (i,  290),  for  McTaggart  takes  from 
the  anti-causationist  a  modest  remnant  of  the  originally  potent 
causal  sequence,  though  he  is  less  certain  about  its  pervasiveness 
than  Alexander — causality  may  not  be  universal  (The  Nature  of 
E. riat r nee,  p.  231). 

The  fortunes  of  the  concept  of  causality  may  be  compared  to 
the  fortunes  of  the  notion  that  chemical  elements  may  be  a  mixture 
of  atoms  with  different  atomic  weights.  The  statistical  method  of 
enquiry  imposed  upon  science  for  many  years,  obliging  it  to  study 
reactions  involving  large  groups  of  atoms,  prevented  the  detection 
cf  the  different  atoms  constituting  these  groups — of  isotopes. 
Crookes  thought  he  had  found  an  element  whose  atoms  differed  in 
weight  because  he  obtained  different  spectra  from  sifted  groups  of 
these  atoms.  His  "meta-elements,"  however,  were  finally  identified 
with  real  elements  and  elements  again  assumed  their  apparent  atomic 
homogeneity.  The  more  effective  methods  of  analysis  of  the  present 


BOOK  REVIEWS  525 

century  have  established  the  existence  of  substances  with  practi- 
cally identical  chemical  and  spectroscopic  qualities  but  different 
atomic  weights  (Aston,  Isotopes,  Ch.  1).  When  causal  sequences 
are  grossly  taken,  the  threads  of  causal  or  determinate,  connection 
are  concealed.  These  connections  were  suspected  and  their  possi- 
bility haunted  the  mind.  But  phenomena  taken  in  the  gross  as 
causes  and  effects  are  liable  to  the  interventions  that  the  cup-and- 
mouth  argument  employs  so  effectively.  Statistical  resumes  in  math- 
ematical formulae  still  more  effectively  conceal  these  threads  of  deter- 
mination that  run  through  the  complexities  of  the  world. 

By  singling  out,  with  more  delicate  analysis,  the  fundamental 
connections  in  the  simple  final  characters  of  the  world,  Dr.  McTag- 
gart  reveals  Intrinsic  Determination  containing  temporal  distinc- 
tions. He  reveals  causal  connections  threading  together  the  com- 
plexities of  empirical  existents.  The  bunches  of  causal  connections, 
of  temporally  distinguishable  Intrinsic  Determinations,  that  repre- 
sent the  gross,  complex  causes  and  effects  of  empirical  life,  often 
have  no  rigid  connection  though  they  may  present  themselves  in 
very  uniform  sequence.  They  are  often  sequent  by  the  general  per- 
mission of  the  universe — the  business  man  regularly  catching  his 
morning  train  because  the  ground  does  not  open  to  swallow  him, 
and  the  human  race  continuing  to  exist  because  the  atmosphere  is 
not  swept  off  into  space.  But  the  conviction  implanted  in  the  human 
mind  by  the  reasonably  trustworthy  regularity  in  its  experience 
seems  to  be.  justified,  though  by  more  ideal  causal  relations  than  the 
first  causal  relations  it  affirms.  Gross  rigid  connections  are  less 
rigid  than  they  first  appear  and  many  sequences  are  broken  or  under- 
stood to  be  breakable.  None  the  less,  the  degree  of  regularity  in 
the.  world,  which  is  very  great,  seems  to  depend  upon  fundamental 
determinations  which  are  often  temporally  connected  or  causal. 

JOSHUA  C.  GREGORY. 

BRADFORD,  ENGLAND. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Senescence.    G.  STANLEY  HALL.    New  York:  D.  Appleton  and  Co. 

1922.    Pp.  xxvii  -f  518. 

In  this  500-page  volume,  with  neither  index  nor  bibliography,  but 
with  a  well-analyzed  table  of  contents,  Dr.  Hall  gives  a  running 
account  of  "how  the  ignorant  and  learned,  the  child,  the  adult  and 
the  old,  savage  and  civilized  man,  pagans  and  Christians,  the  an- 
cient and  the  modern  world,  the  representatives  of  various  sciences, 


526  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOI'Il  V 

and  different  individuals"  have  viewed  the  latter  half  of  life,  "let- 
ing  each  class  >pr;ik  for  itM-lt'. "  Tliis  compendium  of  opinions,  for 
the  most  part  not  critically  synthesized,  is  interspersed  with  the 
author's  own  reflections,  with  experiences  and  autobiographical  in- 
cidents, personal  articles  of  faith,  and  with  reverberations  of  sev- 
eral doctrines  long  associated  with  this  writer, — the  recapitulation 
theory,  the  infantilism  of  women,  the  role  of  unconscious  and  racial 
memories,  and  the  utilization  of  fragmentary  questionnaire  returns. 

Such  a  book  is  not  easily  reviewed,  for  it  is  in  itself  an  organ- 
ized series  of  reviews,  under  chapter  headings.  To  begin  with,  such 
a  book  has  long  been  needed,  for  the  study  of  dotage  has  too  long 
been  limited  to  the  literary  and  medical  accounts  of  pathological 
cases.  Presenting  the  various  opinions,  the  dilemmas  and  the  situa- 
tions of  senility  as  now  on  record  serves  to  expose  a  lack  of  scien- 
tific data  concerning  age  and  ageing,  and  Senescence  should  serve  as 
the  beginning  of  a  really  scientific  study  of  the  latter  half  of  life, 
its  approaches,  duration  and  terminal.  The  author  constantly 
laments  the  non-existence  of  anything  that  could  be  called  a  science 
of  gerontology. 

Chapter  I  on  "The  Youth  of  Old  Age"  reviews  the  general 
drama  of  the  latter  half  of  life,  the  changes  that  come  with  senes- 
cence and  precede  senectitude.  A  series  of  "typical  cases"  is  of- 
fered, which  however,  unfortunately  for  a  science  of  old  age,  repre- 
sent in  the  main  well-marked  clinical  pictures  of  dementia.  "The 
History  of  Old  Age"  in  the  second  chapter  reviews  the  data  of 
longevity  in  plants  and  animals,  treatment  of  the  aged  in  savage, 
ancient,  medieval  and  modern  societies,  and  quotes  many  pictures 
of  the  nature  and  meaning  of  age.  The  "Literature  by  and  on  the 
Aged,"  in  Chapter  III,  relates  in  a  hopeful  vein  the  accomplish- 
ments of  many  old  people  and  reports  an  assorted  series  of  recipes 
for  happy  and  efficient  senility,  ranging  from  licorice,  astrology 
and  cathartics  to  sleep,  piety  and  eugenics.  The  authorities  quoted 
range  from  Walt  Mason  to  N.  S.  Shaler.  Typical  poems  and  quota- 
tions relating  to  age  and  death  are  given. 

Chapter  IV  treats  of  "Statistics  of  Old  Age  and  Its  Care"  and 
includes  a  study  of  mortality  tables  from  the  point  of  view  of  lon- 
gevity and  changes  therein.  These  show  increased  average  length 
of  human  life  and  both  relative  and  absolute  increase  in  the  num- 
ber of  old  people.  The  care  of  the  aged,  old-age  insurance  and 
pensions,  problems  and  methods  of  retirement,  are  all  considered. 
The  importance  of  the  conservation  of  age  is  stressed  and  "a  senes- 
cent league  of  national  dimensions, ' '  with  its  own  journal,  suggested 
by  a  correspondent,  is  favored. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  527 

Under  the  heading  "Medical  Views  and  Treatment,"  summaries 
are  given  in  Chapter  V  of  many  accounts  of  the  causes  and  symp- 
toms of  decay,  and  of  the  physical  basis  of  longevity.  The  view 
that  longevity  is  chiefly  dependent  on  heredity,  though  admittedly 
"doubtless  correct  in  general,"  is  depreciated  because  "it  is  fatal- 
istic and  tends  to  lessen  the  confidence"  in  the  efficacy  of  medical 
administrations.  Nor  is  this  the  only  place  in  the  book  in  which 
views  are  rejected  because  of  their  "psychological  effect,"  in  spite 
of  the  observational  data  on  which  they  are  based.  The  general 
conclusion,  with  respect  to  medicine,  is  that  individual  differences 
among  the  aged  are  much  greater  than  is  usually  recognized,  and 
that  each  must  be  in  the  main  his  own  physician.  Chapter  VI,  on 
"The  Contributions  of  Biology  and  Physiology"  reviews  the  work 
of  Weismann,  Hering,  Semon  (spelled  Simon),  Metchnikoff,  Minot, 
Child,  Loeb,  Carrel,  Steinach,  Voronoff  and  others  on  such  topics 
as  heredity,  growth,  prolonging  life,  rejuvenation,  artificial  pres- 
ervation of  tissues,  endocrinology,  and  gland  transplantation. 
Much  significance  is  attached  to  the  contemporaneous  exploitation 
of  the  sex  glands  and  that  of  the  unconscious  erotic  and  it  is  sug- 
gested that  in  these  related  fields  the  cure  of  man's  most  grievous 
ills  must  be  sought. 

In  Chapter  VII  questionnaire  returns  from  "a  few  score  of 
mostly  eminent  and  some  very  distinguished  people"  are  discussed. 
These  are  admittedly  "far  more  suggestive  than  conclusive"  al- 
though the  selected  replies  tend  more  or  less  constantly  to  be  gen- 
eralized or  taken  as  indications  of  "types."  In  the  next  chapter  on 
"Some  Conclusions"  the  author  gives  vent  to  his  own  reflections 
and  views  and  describes  many  of  his  own  experiences  and  experi- 
ments in  growing  old.  The  main  themes  are  the  physical  and 
mental  hygiene  of  age  and  a  protest  against  the  conventional  at- 
titudes toward  the  old.  Sexual  and  marital  problems,  sleep,  food, 
mood,  emotional  life,  general  mental  and  occupational  adjustments, 
and  the  "Indian  Summers"  of  the  aged  are  considered.  Especially 
emphasized  is  the  preeminence  of  the  old  in  religion,  politics,  phi- 
losophy, morals  and  as  judges.  It  is  this  chapter  that  will  most 
interest  the  general  reader.  In  it,  besides  the  readable  accounts  of 
the  psychology  of  dotage,  the  author  presents  his  personal  views 
and  advocates  his  main  thesis,  "which  is  that  intelligent  and  well 
conserved  senectitude  has  very  important  social  and  anthropologi- 
cal functions  in  the  modern  world  not  hitherto  utilized  or  even 
recognized.  The  chief  of  these  is  most  comprehensively  designated 
by  the  general  term,  synthesis." 


528  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

A  final  chapter  reviews  the  literature  and  opinions  on  the  psy- 
chology of  death  and  the  various  forms  and  determinations  of  the 
hope  for  immortality  or  survival.  Of  special  interest  is  the  advo- 
cacy of  Stekel's  thesis  that  life  is  full  of  "thanatic  symbolism"  and 
that  many  of  the  details  of  poetry,  folk-lore,  myth,  dreams  and 
neuroses,  ordinarily  given  a  sexual  significance  by  the  Freudians, 
may  be  better  treated  as  death  symbols.  "Thanatopsis"  and  "Cross- 
ing the  Bar"  appropriately  close  the  volume. 

Certainly  but  few  topics  or  solutions  have  escaped  the  inquir- 
ing eye  of  Dr.  Hall  in  this  exploration  of  the  literature  of  senility. 
The  reviewer  wishes  that  at  least  one  adjustment  that  seems  to  him 
obviously  to  solve  at  once  many  problems  both  of  infancy  and  of 
senility  had  been  fully  considered,  or  at  least  recognized.  On  the 
one  hand,  society  is  burdened  by  the  prolongation  of  infancy  and 
education.  On  the  other,  it  faces  an  increase  in  the  average  span 
of  life  and  in  the  number  of  the  old.  The  former  need  some  one  to 
care  for  them,  the  latter  something  to  care  for.  Could  not  social 
organization  profit  from  the  skipping  of  a  generation  in  the  pro- 
gram jof  care  ?  How  can  the  old  better  employ  their  preeminent 
judicial  capacity  and  their  power  of  synthesis  than  in  the  training 
of  the  young?  If  children  were,  by  general  expectation,  the  estate 
of  their  grandparents  rather  than  the  property  of  their  fathers  and 
mothers  the  active  generation  would  be  released  from  its  chief 
handicap  and  the  two  problem-generations  both  provided  with  care 
and  motivation  compatible  with  their  dignity.  Dr.  Hall  makes 
much  of  "the  eternal  war  between  the  young  and  the  old"  and  as- 
serts in  the  same  chapter  that  in  the  aged  "there  is  a  new  type  of 
interest  in  young  people  and  in  children."  It  seems  far  from  ab- 
surd to  suggest  that  the  skipping  of  a  generation  in  the  social  pro- 
gram of  care  and  responsibility  might  utilize  this  new  interest  in 
the  resolution  of  that  warfare,  and  at  the '  same  time  afford  so- 
ciety an  added  basis  of  stability. 

H.  L.  HOLLINGWORTH. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

The  Thirteen  Principal  Upanishads,  translated  from  the  Sanskrit, 
with  an  outline  of  the  Upanishads  and  an  annotated  bibliog- 
raphy. ROBERT  ERNEST  HUME.  Oxford  University  Press.  1921. 

This  is  a  book  of  which  American  scholarship  has  a  right  to 
be  proud.  "With  little  fear  of  contradiction  it  may  be  called  the 
first  adequate  English  translation  of  the  Upanishads.  It  is  the 
result  of  many  years'  careful  work  and  of  a  life-time  of  preparation. 
Himself  born  in  India  and  brought  up  in  its  intellectual  atmosphere, 


BOOK  REVIEWS  529 

familiar  with  the  vernacular  as  well  as  with  Sanskrit,  intimate  with 
Indian  as  well  as  with  European  scholars,  at  home  in  both  Oriental 
and  Occidental  thought,  Professor  Hume  was  in  an  unusually  favor- 
able position  for  rendering  the  service  which  he  has  so  painstakingly 
performed. 

The  book  contains,  in  addition  to  the  scholarly  translation  of  the 
thirteen  principal  Upanishads  in  what  is  thought  to  be  their  chrono- 
logical order,  a  seventy-page  Outline  of  the  philosophy  of  the  writ- 
ings translated,  a  discriminating  bibliography,  and  a  carefully  made 
Sanskrit  and  general  index.  For  the  special  student,  the  bibliog- 
raphy by  itself  would  be  of  as  much  value  as  many  an  excellent 
book.  It  is  a  selected,  classified,  and  annotated  bibliography,  giving 
not  only  the  title  and  author,  but  also  a  brief  account  and  evalua- 
tion of  all  the  important  translations  of  the  Upanishads,  of  the  chief 
editions  of  their  texts,  and  of  the  more  valuable  linguistic  and  ex- 
pository treatises  concerning  them. 

The  introductory  Outline  is  an  admirable  piece  of  work,  tracing 
the  probable  development  of  the  Brahma  concept  into  the  first 
Indian  pantheism,  the  parallel  development  of  the  Atman  concept, 
the  identification  of  the  two,  the  rise  of  the  distinction  between 
phenomenon  and  noumenon  as  a  result  of  the  apparent  conflict  be- 
tween the  many  and  the  one,  and  the  reconciliation  of  the  two  in 
a  form  of  Absolute  Idealism.  It  is  perhaps  unfortunate  that  Pro- 
fessor Hume  so  often  refers  to  this  final  synthesis  as  "Pantheism" 
— a  name  which  surely  should  be  reserved  for  a  more  realistic  world 
view.  It  is  questionable,  moreover,  whether  Professor  Hume's  ex- 
position of  the  ultimate  nature  of  Brahma  and  of  union  with  It 
really  gets  to  the  bottom  of  the  thought  of  the  Upanishads.  I  would 
at  least  suggest  that  the  real  meaning  of  these  ancient  thinkers  was 
that  this  final  union  is  not  to  be  understood  as  "an  unconscious  con- 
dition," but  rather  as  a  hypothetically  pure  intuition,  consciousness 
without  an  object, — comparable  in  some  respects  to  Aristotle's 
v6rjffi.s  vo^Vews  (cf.  Brihad-Aranyaka,  IV,  3  and  5,  Kena,  4-8).  Of 
course  this  view  has  difficulties  of  its  own,  but  it  points  a  way  out 
of  some  of  the  difficulties  which  Professor  Hume  seems  to  regard 
as  insuperable. 

As  to  the  translation  itself,  too  much  praise  can  hardly  be  given 
to  its  conscientious  scholarship  and  to  the  aids  which  it  offers  the 
student  for  understanding  what  the  Upanishads  actually  say  and 
probably  mean.  In  this  respect  it  is  superior  to  both  the  other 
great  translations,  namely,  Eucken's  and  Max  Miiller's.  Eucken's 
is,  of  course,  a  much  more  inclusive  work  than  Professor  Hume's — 
as  its  title  indicates,  "Sechzig  Upanishads  des  Veda" — and  it  is  a 


530  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

work  of  equal  scholarship.    In  the  opinion,  however,  of  several  San- 
skrit scholars  of  eminence,  it  is  not  so  close  to  the  original  as  is  Pro- 
fessor Hume's;  and  the  occasional  rendering  of  the  verse  portions 
of  the  text  into  doggerel  detracts  somewhat  from  its  literary  charm. 
Over  Max  Miiller's  English  translation,  Dr.  Hume's  work  has  even 
greater  advantages.     The  older  translation  is  considerably  farther 
from  the  original  and  it  is  regularly  impossible  to  distinguish  within 
it  what  the  Upanishads  actually  said  and  what  Max  Miiller  added. 
The  shortcomings  of  Miiller's  version  have  long  been  recognized, 
and  are,  indeed,  undeniable.    Yet  I  can  not  refrain  from  saying  one 
good  word  for  his  great  book.    Just  because  of  the  greater  freedom 
with  which  he  treated  the  text  he  was  able  to  give  full  swing  to  his 
very  great  literary  power,  and  the  result  was  a  translation  which 
from  the  point  of  view  of  English  was  a  work  of  art.    The  quiet  elo- 
quence of  Max  Miiller's  noble  prose  in  many  of  the  finer  passages  is 
quite  unmatched  in  any  other  translation  of  the  Upanishads  with 
which  I  am  acquainted.     Like  Gilbert  Murray's  renderings  of  the 
Greek  dramatists,  it  takes  many  liberties  with  the  original ;  but  one 
may  well  question  whether  the  general  impression  which  the  be- 
ginner takes  away  from  both  Murray  and  Miiller  is  not  more  true 
to  the  original  work  as  a  whole  than  he  would  get  from  the  more 
literal  and  scholarly  translations.     Personally,  I  am  glad  that  it 
was  Max  Miiller  who  introduced  me  to  the  Upanishads.     I  shall 
never  forget  the  tremendous  impression  I  got  from  my  first  reading 
of  the  Katha  and  the  Brihad-Aranyaka,  in  his  version,  twenty-five 
years   ago.     If  I  had   begun   with  either  Eucken's  or  Professor 
Hume's  more  literal  presentations  I  am  not  sure  I  should  have  re- 
ceived any  such  impression  or  should  have  taken  away  with  me  any 
such  desire  as  I  actually  did  to  know  more  of  these  unique  ancient 
writings.     I  do  not  think,  therefore,  that  Max  Miiller's  translation 
has  as  yet  been  fully  replaced  or  ever  will  be.     The  student  will 
still  do  well  to  begin  with  his  translation  and  go  on  for  his  more 
exact  study  to  Eucken  and  Hume. 

Tn  spite  of  the  fact,  however,  that  in  the  swing  of  its  diction 
Professor  Hume's  translation  is  necessarily  inferior  to  Max  Miiller's 
— necessarily  so  if  it  was  to  have  the  greater  merit  of  literal  render- 
ing— it  may  well  be  called  the  first  adequate  English  translation  of 
the  Upanishads.  Professor  Hume  has  made  it  possible  for  the 
student  of  Indian  philosophy  and  religion  who  has  no  Sanskrit  to 
with  a  great  deal  of  exactness  what  it  is  these  ancient  books 
contain.  And  it  may  be  added  that  few  books  are  moro  worthy  of 
study  for  all  who  are  interested  in  the  human  mind  and  human 
thought  than  these  age-long  guides  to  India's  meditation.  Professor 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  531 

Hume  has  therefore  done  a  work  for  which  he  should  have  the 
profound  thanks  of  a  host  of  readers. 

JAMES  BISSETT  PRATT. 
WILLIAMS  COLLEGE. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

REVUE  DE  METAPHYSIQUE  ET  DE  MORALE.  XXIX,  No.  2.  April- 
June,  1922.  Le  realisme  philosophique  en  Amerique:  R.  B.  Perry. 
Les  facteurs  kantiens  de  la  philosophic  allemande  de  la  fin  du 
XVIII6  siecle  et  du  commencement  du  XIX6  (suite)  :  V.  Delbos. 
La  philohophie  d'O.  Hamelin:  D.  Parodi. 

THE  MONIST.  XXXII,  No.  3.  July,  1922.  The  Philosophy 
of  Possibility:  James  Lindsay.  Dewey's  Theory  of  Value:  T.  V. 
Smith.  History  and  Philosophy:  C.  Delisle  Burns.  The  Relation 
of  Space  and  Geometry  to  Experience  (Concluded)  :  Norbert 
Wiener.  The  Failure  of  Critical  Realism:  J.  E.  Turner.  Ein- 
stein's Theory  of  Relativity  Considered  from  the  Epistemological 
Standpoint:  Ernst  Cassirer.  The  Psycho-Genesis  of  Space:  C. 
0.  Weber.  The  Realism  of  Tongiorgi :  James  Lindsay.  The  Fal- 
lacy of  Exclusive  Scientific  Methodology:  Wesley  R.  Wells. 

MIND.  XXXI,  No.  123.  July,  1922.  The  Philosophy  of 
Chance :  F.  Y.  Edgeworth.  Sense-Data  and  Sensible  Appearances 
in  Size-Distance  Perception:  H.  N.  Randle.  Mr.  Russell's  Theory 
of  the  External  World :  C.  A.  Strong.  Visual  Images,  Words  and 
Dreams:  Joshua  C.  Gregory.  Discussions:  A  Word  About  "Co- 
herence": B.  Bosanquet.  Relativity,  Scientific  and  Philosophical: 
J.  E.  Turner. 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW.  XXIX,  No.  4.  July,  1922.  Psychology 
and  Psychiatry :  Shepherd  Ivory  Franz.  What  is  Psychology  ? : 
B.  H.  Bode.  Suggestions  for  a  Compromise  of  Existing  Controver- 
sies in  Psychology :  W.  B.  Pillsbury.  An  Analysis  of  Psychological 
Language  Data :  J.  R.  Kant  or.  A  New  Approach  to  the  Study  of 
Genius:  Lewis  M.  Terman.  A  Practical  Definition  of  Character: 
Raymond  0.  Filter.  Discussions:  Conscious  Analysis,  Introspec- 
tion, and  Behaviorism:  F.  A.  C.  Perrin.  The  Term  "Practise": 
E.  B.  Titchener. 

Chiocchetti,  Emilio:  La  Filosofia  de  Giovanni  Gentile.  Milan: 
Societa  editrice  Vita  e  Pensiero.  1922.  480  pp. 

Gentile,  Giovanni :  The  Reform  of  Education.  Authorized 
translation  by  Dino  Bigongiari.  An  Introduction  by  Croce.  New 
York :  Harcourt,  Brace  and  Company.  1922.  xi  -f-  250  pp. 


532  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Williams,  James  Mickel :  Principles  of  Social  Psychology.  New 
York :  Alfred  A.  Knopf.  1922.  xii  +  458  pp. 

The  Works  of  Aristotle:  De  Caelo.  De  Generatione  et  Comip- 
tione.  Translated  into  English  by  J.  L.  Stocks.  New  York:  Ox- 
ford University  Press.  1922.  $3.35. 

Biavaschi,  G.  B. :  La  Crisi  attuale  della  Filosofia  del  diritto. 
Milan:  Societa  editrice  Vita  e  Pensiero.  1922.  336  pp. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

The  Joint  Meeting  of  the  Eastern  and  Western  Divisions  of  the 
American  Philosophical  Association  will  be  held  at  Union  Theo- 
logical Seminary,  New  York  City,  December  27,  28  and  29.  Pro- 
fessor Dewey  will  deliver  the  Paul  Cams  Lectures,  which  will  be 
four  in  number. 

Dr.  H.  M.  Halverson,  of  Clark  University,  has  been  appointed 
professor  of  psychology  at  the  University  of  Maine. 

Dr.  Floyd  H.  Allport,  of  Harvard  University,  has  been  ap- 
pointed associate  professor  of  psychology  at  the  University  of  North 
Carolina. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  20  SEPTEMBER  28,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE 

II.  PROFESSOR  DEWEY'S  Tertium  Quid 

T  T  would  appear  from  their  title  that  the  chief  purpose  of  Pro- 
-*-  fessor  Dewey's  recent  articles  in  this  JOURNAL*  is  to  vindicate 
a  third  variety  of  realism  which  is  neither  dualistic  nor  monistic. 
The  considerations  which  seem  to  him  to  support  this,  however,  are 
fully  broached  only  in  his  second  article,  to  which  I  now  turn. 

1.  The  first  question  which  it  would  seem  pertinent  to  ask  is 
whether  such  a  tertium  quid  is  logically  conceivable,  i.e.,  whether 
the  two  other  species  of  realism  do  not  exhaust  the  possibilities  of 
the  genus.  Upon  this  question  Mr.  Dewey  does  not  neglect  to 
touch.  He  finds  that — in  consequence  of  a  general  "addiction  to 
uncritical  use  of  the  principle  of  excluded  middle" — I  have  too 
hastily  assumed  that  "the  disjunction  between  monistic  and  dual- 
istic realism  is  exhaustive.  There  remains  pluralistic  realism.  .  .  . 
The  things  which  are  taken  as  meaning  or  intending  other  things 
are  infinitely  diversified,  and  so  are  the  things  meant.  Smoke 
stands  for  fire,  an  odor  for  a  rose,  different  odors  for  different 
things,  .  .  .  and  so  on  ad  infinitum."2  This  is  much  as  if  one 
should  argue  that  the  division  of  the  class  of  finite  whole  numbers 
into  odd  and  even  is  not  exhaustive  because  "there  remain  also 
telephone  numbers."  In  other  words,  Mr.  Dewey's  "pluralistic" 
species  of  realism,  as  his  illustrations  show,  is  distinguished  by  means 
of  a  fundamentum  divisionis  different  from  that  by  which  dualistic 
and  monistic  realism  are  distinguished.  By  the  last-mentioned  is 
meant  the  doctrine  that  in  perception  and  thought  the  object  known 
is  always  present  immediately,  without  duplication  or  "representa- 
tion, ' '  in  the  cognitive  experience ;  by  dualistic  realism  is  meant  the 
doctrine  which  denies  this  universal  direct  presence  of  the  thing 
known  in  the  knowing,  and  declares  that  the  object  of  knowledge 

i" Realism  without  Monism  or  Dualism,"   XIX,  pp.   309-317;    351-361; 
here  cited  as  B.  M.  D. 
2  R.  M.  D.,  p.  356. 

533 


534  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

may  be,  and  in  at  least  some  cases  can  be  shown  to  be,  existentially 
other  than  the  content  of  knowledge.  Since  the  essence  of  the 
second  theory  is  the  negation  of  the  immediacy  asserted  by  the 
first,  the  dichotomy  is  complete ; 8  no  other  realistic  view  is  possible 
with  respect  to  the  matter  to  which  the  doctrines  in  question  refer, 
namely,  the  universal  identity  or  possible  non-identity  of  object 
and  content.  Mr.  Dewey's  "pluralistic"  class  does  not  lie  outside 
this  two-fold  division ;  it  might  be  a  sub-species  of  one  of  the  classes 
mentioned.  Certainly  there  is  nothing  in  epistemological  dualism 
which  requires  anyone  to  deny  that  "different  odors  stand  for  dif- 
ferent things,"  or  even  that  "the  things  which  mean  other  things, 
and  likewise  the  things  meant,  are  infinitely  diversified."  "Dual- 
istic  realism"  does  not,  as  Mr.  Dewey's  antithesis  would  seem  to 
imply,  mean  the  theory  that  there  are  only  two  "things"  in  the 
universe. 

And,  in  fact,  it  turns  out  that  his  own  view  is  epistemologically 
dualistic,  in  one  sense  of  the  word  "knowledge,"  and  monistic  if 
the  word  is  used  in  another  sense.  "Wherever  inference  or  reflec- 
tion comes  in,"  we  are  told — and  Mr.  Dewey  would  "not  call  any- 
thing knowledge  in  a  logical  or  intellectual  sense  unless  they  do 
come  in — there  is,  clearly,  mediation  of  an  object  by  some  other 
entity  which  points  to,  signifies,  or  represents  it."  Here  is  an 
obvious  dualism.  But,  he  adds,  "knowledge  in  the  complete  sense 
of  the  word"  requires  that  "the  object"  shall  be  "  'reached'  even- 
tually," that  "the  indication  or  signifying"  be  "borne  out,  verified, 
in  something  immediately  present."  Until  this  is  accomplished, 
we  have  (in  spite  of  the  definition  of  a  different  kind  of  "knowl- 
edge" cited  just  above)  only  "a  claim  to  knowledge,"  not  knowl- 
edge itself.  Here,  then,  since  (apparently)  the  actual  object  known 
—though  it  gets  its  "cognitive  status"  from  "a  prior  mediation "- 
is  required  to  be  "immediately  experienced,"  we  have  an  equally 
obvious  epistemological  monism.  But  this  employment  of  the  term 
"knowledge"  in  two  senses  does  not  show  that  the  disjunction 
which  Mr.  Dewey  challenges  is  not  exhaustive.  When  he  is  using 
the  term  in  any  one  sense,  his  account  of  knowledge  falls  on  one 

•  One  might,  of  course,  be  a  dualistic  realist  with  respect  to  some  parts  of 
the  field  of  supposed  knowledge  (e.g.,  to  the  objects  of  thought)  and  monistic 
with  respect  to  other  parts  (e.g.,  the  objects  of  perception).  But  the  distinc- 
tion of  meaning  (not  of  application)  of  the  two  theories  remains  unchanged — 
as  does  the  irrelevancy  of  Mr.  Dewey's  remark  about  the  "pluralistic"  variety. 
In  other  words,  with  respect  to  any  given  known  object,  a  realist  must  take 
either  the  monistic  or  the  dualistic  view;  and  the  application  of  the  dualistic 
to  any  object  contradicts  the  universal  proposition  which  defines  the  position 
understood  by  the  term  "monistic  realism." 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE  535 

side  or  the  other  of  the  antithesis;  and  even  with  the  aid  of  both 
senses,  it  never  succeeds  in  offering  us  an  example  of  any  third  way 
of  knowing. 

In  the  main,  it  is  epistemological  dualism  that  prevails  in  Mr. 
Dewey's  paper.  In  the  "knowledge"  which  constitutes  most  of 
our  science,  things  are  known — as  he  not  merely  concedes  but  in- 
sists— not  by  their  direct  presence  at  the  moment  of  judgment  about 
them,  but  through  "surrogates."  The  geologist  does  not,  after  all, 
"immediately  experience"  extinct  animals,  even  "eventually."  But 
Mr.  Dewey's  essential  contention  is  that  such  epistemological  dual- 
ism does  not  imply  a  psycho-physical  dualism.  The  "surrogates," 
he  seeks  to  show,  are  not  psychical  entities,  such  as  "ideas"  or 
"mental  states,"  but  simply  other  objective  "things." 

2.  To  understand  his  reasons  for  this  contention,  it  is  necessary 
to  examine  his  remarks  about  "meaning,"  which  seem  to  me  the 
most  significant  part  of  the  second  paper.  "The  problem  of  mean- 
ing," Mr.  Strong  has  recently  said,  "is  well  adapted  to  take  us  to 
the  roots  of  things."4  With  this  Mr.  Dewey  would  apparently 
agree.  "Meanings,"  he  writes,  "are  the  characteristic  things  in  in- 
tellectual experience.  They  are  the  heart  of  every  logical  func- 
tion." But  his  treatment  of  this  all-important  notion  seems  to  me 
throughout  ambiguous,  sometimes  inconsistent,  and  in  great  part 
irrelevant  to  the  issues  raised  in  my  paper  in  Essays  in  Critical 
Realism,  to  which  he  is  replying.  Three  distinct,  though  not  by 
him  clearly  and  steadily  distinguished,  senses  of  "meaning"  are 
discoverable  in  his  argument. 

(a)  In  the  more  frequent  and  more  definite  passages  on  the 
subject,  "meaning"  signifies  the  relation  or  "function"  of  causal 
or  other  implication  between  facts  or  existents.  One  thing  "means" 
another  when  its  existence,  or  presence  in  experience,  furnishes  the 
ground  for  a  valid  inference  to  the  existence  or  empirical  occur- 
rence of  the  other.  Thus  smoke  "means"  fire,  an  odor  "means" 
a  flower  still  to  be  smelled,  the  oscillation  of  the  needle  of  a  seismo- 
graph "means"  a  distant  earthquake.  In  this  sense,  Mr.  Dewey 
observes,  meanings  as  well  as  things  meant  are  objective;  but  they 
(meanings)  are  not  physical,  nor  are  they  mental  "in  any  psychical 
dualistic  existential  sense. ' ' 5  Mr.  Dewey  is,  indeed,  willing  to 
admit  the  word  ' '  mental ' '  into  the  vocabulary  of  philosophy  in  this 
connection,  but  only  in  a  new  sense,  namely,  to  designate  any  entity 
(e.g.,  a  physical  one)  in  so  far  as  it  is  conceived  as  "exercising  the 
function  of  being  a  surrogate  of  some  absent  thing."  But  this 

*  Mind,  January,  1922,  p.  71. 
»  B.  M.  D.,  p.  358. 


536  JOURNAL  OF  PIIILOSOPII  Y 

terminological  concession  does  not  imply  that  the  object  pc 
meaning  only  by  grace  of  the  activity  of  some  mind  or  knower ;  for 
we  are  told  that  "the  relation,  connection  or  mediation  of  one  thing 
by  another  is,"  rather,  "an  essential  feature  of  the  subject-matter 
of  knowledge."6  Or,  as  it  is  written  in  an  earlier  paper  of  Mr. 
Dewey's,  "meanings  are  intrinsic;  they  have  no  instrumental  or 
subservient  office  because  they  have  no  office  at  all.  They  are  as 
much  qualities  of  the  objects  in  the  situation  as  are  red  and  black, 
hard  and  soft,  square  and  round. " 7  It  is,  to  be  sure,  difficult  to 
see  how  this  is  to  be  reconciled  with  the  repeated  remark  that  it  is 
only  when  physical  things  "become  implicated  in  a  reflective  in- 
quiry"— only  when  we  "ask  what  they  stand  for  or  indicate"  and 
"when  it  is  asserted  that  they  mean  or  support  a  certain  conclu- 
sion"— that  they  "acquire  a  representative  capacity  which  they 
did  not  inherently  possess,"  or  "exercise  a  representative  function, 
though  not  in  (their)  own  existence  representations."  8  However, 
it  is  fortunately  not  essential  to  my  purpose  to  try  to  harmonize 
Mr.  Dewey's  utterances  on  this  point. 

What  seems  fairly  clear  is  that,  in  the  first  sense  of  meaning,  the 
thing  which  means  and  the  thing  meant  are  both  physical  objects; 
that  the  relation  between  them  is  not  necessarily  one  of  similarity; 
and  that  the  "meaning"  itself,  is  neither  psychical  nor  physical, 
but  a  "neutral  entity"  or  "essence."9 

(6)  But  a  footnote  gives  us  a  second  definition  of  "meanings": 
"of  course,  upon  my  theory  they  are,  existentially  speaking,  the 
operations  involved  in  any  situation  having  a  cognitive  refer- 
ence. ' ' 10  These  ' '  operations, ' '  I  take  it,  are  not  essences,  but  defi- 
nite temporal  activities  performed  by  cognitive  agents  or,  if  the 
expression  is  preferred,  by  intelligent  animals;  and  we  are  else- 
where expressly  told  that  they  are  physical.11  No  particular  use, 
however,  seems  to  be  made  of  this  definition  in  Mr.  Dewey's  present 
argument. 

«  R.  M.  D.,  p.  354 ;  italics  in  original. 

•  E$says  in  Experimental  Logic,  1916,  p.  17.    The  "situation"  referred  to 
is  "the  situation  which  follows  upon  reflection."    If  this  signifies  that,  unless 
they  had  been  reflected  upon,  the  objects  would  not  possess  ' '  meaning ' '  at  all, 
the  sentence  would  suggest  rather  a  subjectivistic  conception  of  meaning.    But 
the  context  of  the  passage  seems  to  indicate  that  Mr.  Dewey  here  is  writing  in 
his  realistic  rather  than  his  idealistic  or  "immediate  empiricist"  vein. 

•  B.  M.  D.,  p.  352. 

•  £.  M.  D.,  p.  357.     Of  this  surprising  resort  of  a  pragmatist  to  logical 
realism  I  shall  speak  further  below. 

10  R.  M.  D.,  p.  358,  n.  9. 
«  B.  L.,  p.  14. 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE  537 

Now  if  these  two  were  the  only  sorts  of  "meaning"  which  Mr. 
Dewey  recognized  as  pertinent  to  the  experience  called  knowing,  it 
is  quite  true  that  no  argument  for  the  presence  of  anything  "psy- 
chical or  mental  as  a  term  in  the  judging  process"  could  be  drawn 
from  any  premise  admitted  by  him.  For  in  the  one  case,  two  of 
the  factors  concerned  (the  thing  which  means  and  the  thing  meant) 
are  described  as  objective  physical  things,  while  the  third  is  ap- 
parently regarded  as  a  real  neutral  or  logical  entity;  while  in  the 
other  case  all  three  factors  are  described  as  physical.  There  is, 
however,  unmistakably  distinguishable  at  certain  points  in  Mr. 
Dewey 's  reasoning  a  third  kind  of  "meaning";  and  it  is  this  kind 
alone  which  is  relevant  to  those  conclusions  of  mine  which  Mr. 
Dewey  controverts. 

(c)  This  third  sense  appears  in  those  passages  in  which  Mr. 
Dewey  recognizes  that,  whenever  thought  occurs,  something  must 
necessarily  be  "  present-as-absent. "  This  obviously  will  not  fit 
into  the  first  account  of  meaning.  In  that  account  we  were  told 
that  "there  is  something  indubitably  present,  say,  smoke,"  and 
that  it  is  this  that  means  or  represents  the  "something  absent, 
say,  fire."  But,  clearly,  in  the  case  supposed  the  smoke  is  not 
present-as-absent;  it  is  just  present,  an  immediate  perceptual 
datum.  It  is  rather,  as  Mr.  Dewey  himself  goes  on  to  note,  the  fire 
that  ' '  is  presented  as  absent,  as  intended. ' ' 12  And  if  the  fire  is 
"presented,"  or  made  present,  it  is  the  presented  fire — not,  as  in 
the  first  account,  the  smoke — that  means  or  represents  the  absent 
fire.  (There  is,  of  course,  an  absent  fire  somehow  concerned  in  the 
business,  else  no  inference  would  be  necessary.)  And  the  relation 
between  that  which  means  and  that  which  is  meant  is,  in  this  sort 
of  meaning,  necessarily  one  of  similarity,  at  least  of  pattern  or 
relational  schema.  A  fire  obviously  does  not  become  "presented," 
or  present-as-absent,  solely  by  virtue  of  the  presence  in  experience 
of  something  that  is  not  a  fire,  and  is  not  like  a  fire,  and  is  in  no 
sense  absent.  It  is  not  smoke-characters  but  fire-characters  that 
must  be  given,  and  yet  referred  to  a  not-present  temporal  or  spatial 
locus,  "in  any  situation  having  a  cognitive  reference"  to  a  fire. 
But  this,  of  course,  is  simply  the  ordinary  dualistic  conception  of 
ideas  or  images  which  can  "re-present"  absent  objects  because  they 
in  some  degree  resemble  or  reproduce  them.  To  some  sort  of  pre- 
sentative  dualism,  in  short,  Mr.  Dewey  is  committed  as  soon  as  he 
acknowledges,  with  respect  to  the  absent  fire  inferred  from  pres- 
ent smoke,  that  "it  is  not  a  case  of  sheer  absence,  such  as  total 

"  B.  M.  D.,  p.  354. 


538  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOI'Il  Y 

ignorance  would  imply."1*  At  the  moment  when  he  wrote  these 
words,  Mr.  Dewey  must  have  had  at  least  a  transitory  realization 
of  the  fact  that  to  constitute  a  knowledge  of  an  absent  fire  a  pres- 
ent smoke  is  not  enough ;  that  the  fire  too  must  in  some  fashion  be 
recognized  as  a  part  of  the  present  content  of  the  experience;  and 
yet  that,  since  the  actual  fire  is  truly  absent,  it  can  not,  so  to  say, 
also  be  present  in  propria  persona,  but  must  be  represented  by  a 
sort  of  deputy-fire,  a  true  "surrogate." 

What  prevents  Mr.  Dewey  from  seeing  the  dualistic  implica- 
tions of  this  third  sort  of  meaning  is  apparently  a  confusion  of  the 
type  pointed  out  in  my  previous  paper — a  tendency  to  fluctuate  be- 
tween two  or  more  senses  of  an  ambiguous  term  or  proposition,  and 
to  use  arguments  based  upon  the  one  sense  to  justify  the  rejection 
of  unwelcome  conclusions  that  would  follow  from  the  other.  In 
the  present  instance  he  seems  to  treat  the  first  and  third  senses  of 
"meaning"  as  interchangeable;  and  since  he  is  able  to  show  that 
the  first,  as  defined,  has  no  objectionably  duali.stic  consequences,  he 
fails  to  see  the  consequences  of  the  third.  All  that  he  has  to 
say  about  the  first  is,  in  fact,  irrelevant  not  merely  to  the  particular 
issue  which  I  had  raised,  but  also  to  the  cognitive  experience  in 
general.  An  "objective"  or  "intrinsic"  reference  of  one  physical 
thing  to  another  is  not  the  same  as  an  apprehension  of  that  refer- 
ence. "A  thing,  res,  actually  present,  smoke,  rock"  may  to  the  top 
of  its  bent  objectively  mean  "something  else  of  the  same  order  of 
existence  as  itself,  a  fire,  or  geologic  animal";  but  in  doing  so  it 
presumably  does  not  recreate,  bring  into  temporal  coexistence  with 
itself,  extinct  animals  or  dead  fires.  Such  a  meaning  is  known,  how- 
ever, only  when  there  are  simultaneously  given  in  the  field  of  aware- 
ness of  a  reflective  organism  both  the  "thing  actually  present,"  and 
the  "presentation"  of  the  something  else  which  is  not  actually  pres- 
ent, and  which  may  at  the  moment  of  the  experience  be  physically 
non-existent.  A  present  rock  is  not,  by  itself,  the  thought  of  a  de- 
ceased dinosaur,  nor  a  smoke-cloud  here  the  thought  of  a  spent  fire 
beyond  the  mountains. 

3.  Does,  then,  the  epistemological  dualism  involved  in  the  kind 
of  "meaning"  which  is  essential  to  cognition  lead  to  psycho-physical 
dualism  f  The  reasons  which  have  seemed  to  me  to  require  (of  a 
realist)  an  affirmative  answer  to  this  question  Mr.  Dewey  states 
briefly  but  not  incorrectly:  " Present-as-absent,  or  the  presence  of 
the  absent,  is  an  impossibility  as  regards  any  physical  thing. 
Hence  there  is  an  admission  of  a  psychical  entity."  For  "psychi- 
cal" in  my  usage  means  any  indubitable  content  of  experience 
i*  B.  M.  D.,  p.  354. 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE  539 

which  can  not  be  assigned  to  the  physical  world  as  simultaneously 
constituted.  To  this  argument,  however,  Mr.  Dewey  takes  excep- 
tion on  the  ground  that  it  unwarrantably  "assumes  an  exhaustive 
disjunction  between  the  physical  and  psychical."  My  unhappy 
addiction  to  the  principle  of  excluded  middle  has,  it  seems,  again 
been  my  undoing;  it  has  caused  me  to  ignore  "the  growing  num- 
ber of  persons  who  hold  that  certain  entities  are  neutral  to  the  dis- 
tinction of  psychical  and  physical,"  and  to  "assert  by  implication 
that  all  meanings,  relations,  activity  systems,  functions,  affairs  like 
mathematical  entities,  etc.,  .  .  .  are  psychical."  Until  I  have 
"wrestled  with  the  question  of  essence  in  its  bearing  upon  the  ex- 
haustiveness  of  the  disjunction  between  the  physical  and  the  psy- 
chical, and  until  many  non-pragmatists  are  disposed  of, ' '  Mr.  Dewey 
feels  entitled  "to  leave  the  matter  here." 

With  respect  to  the  principle  of  excluded  middle  I  am  afraid 
that  I  am  a  confirmed  habitue;  for  I  still  find  myself  convinced  of 
the  exhaustiveness  of  the  particular  disjunction  presupposed  by 
the  argument  in  question.  Mr.  Dewey 's  criticism  of  it  is,  to  be 
plain,  beside  the  mark  in  three  respects: 

(a)  The  "question  of  essences"  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  uni- 
verse of  discourse  with  which  my  discussion  was,  and  is,  obviously 
concerned,  viz.,  the  universe  of  particular  concrete  existents  in  time. 
Within  that  universe  a  logically  exhaustive  disjunction  of  the  physi- 
cal and  the  psychical  can  very  well  be  made  out — and  that  wholly 
without  prejudice  to  the  doctrine  of  the  "neutrality"  of  purely 
logical  entities.  A  given  bit  of  empirical  content  present  here  and 
now  in  my  consciousness,  and  possessing  the  attribute  of  extension, 
either  is  or  is  not  assignable  to  the  "public"  spatial  order  of  the 
physical  sciences  and  to  the  system  to  which  the  equations  of  ther- 
modynamics apply.  And  the  sole  issue  with  which  my  inquiry  had 
to  do  was  whether  there  are  any  such  concrete  particulars  in  experi- 
ence, the  characteristics  of  which  forbid  their  allocation  to  the 
physical  world.  If  there  are  such,  their  non-physical  status  does 
not  prove  that  they  are  mere  "essences."  The  argument,  there- 
fore, for  their  psychical  character — in  the  sense  defined — remains 
entirely  unaffected  by  Mr.  Dewey 's  Macedonian  cry  to  the  logical 
realists. 

(6)  Moreover,  the  particular  class  of  things  of  which  the  psy- 
chical character  was  asserted  was  not,  as  Mr.  Dewey  seems  to  sup- 
pose, the  class  of  "meanings,"  in  the  sense  in  which  he  here  uses 
the  term.  So  far  as  the  present  argument  goes,  a  meaning  may  be 
as  "neutral"  as  anyone  may  choose  to  think  it — if  it  is  simply  a 
logical  relation  subsisting  between  two  concrete  things.  In  the 


540  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

dualistic  view,  the  psychical  entity  involved  is  primarily  the  thing 
which  means — not  the  "meaning"  nor,  necessarily,  the  thing  meant. 
It  is,  in  other  words,  the  idea  that  stands  for  an  absent  real  object. 
It  is  the  same  entity  to  which  Mr.  Dewey  ascribes  the  status  of 
present-as-absent ;  and  this,  clearly,  is  not  a  mere  essence. 

(c)  Finally,  I  should — before  reading  Mr.  Dewey 's  last  paper — 
have  thought  it  wholly  redundant  to  discuss  logical  realism  in  an 
essay  devoted  specifically  to  an  examination  of  the  position  of  the 
pragmatists.  For  I  had  supposed  that  no  doctrine  could  be  more 
foreign  to  their  position.  Now,  I  confess,  I  am  uncertain  how  Mr. 
Dewey  really  stands  on  this  matter.  Much  of  his  language  seems 
to  suggest  a  belief  in  an  independently  existing  realm  of  logical 
reals.  But  I  take  refuge  again  in  an  excluded  middle !  Either  Pro- 
fessor Dewey  is  a  logical  realist  or  he  is  not.  If  he  is,  we  shall  all, 
assuredly,  have  to  revise  profoundly  our  conceptions  of  the  mean- 
ing and  doctrinal  affinities  of  pragmatism;  yet,  as  has  been  shown, 
the  status  of  the  particular  question  here  under  discussion  would 
remain  untouched.  If  he  is  not  an  adherent  of  that  view,  the  in- 
troduction of  it  into  the  discussion  would  seem  reminiscent  of  the 
well-known  red  herring.  For  there  is  not,  I  believe,  any  generally 
accepted  rule  of  the  etiquette  of  philosophical  debate  which  re- 
quires that  a  critic,  before  examining  the  opinions  which  a  given 
school  of  philosophers  hold,  shall  first  refute  the  opinions  which 
they  do  not  hold. 

Since,  to  my  great  regret,  I  have  not  thus  far  in  these  papers 
been  able  to  express  a  very  large  measure  of  agreement  with  Mr. 
Dewey,  I  shall  take  as  the  text  for  a  summing-up  a  sentence  of  his 
which  seems  to  me  both  true  and  truly  "pragmatic."  "Imagina- 
tive recovery  of  the  bygone,"  he  has  written,  "is  indispensable  to 
successful  invasion  of  the  future. ' ' 14  That  embodies  neatly  in  a 
single  phrase  four  truths  about  our  intertemporal  cognition  which 
underlie  both  man's  life  of  action  and  his  life  of  feeling.  Drawn 
out  into  full  and  formal  statement,  the  propositions  implicit  in  this 
pregnant  sentence  are  these:  (a)  It  is  things  actually  "bygone" 
that  man  requires  to  know,  if  his  adventure  into  the  future  is  to  be 
guided  by  intelligence.  Hence  it  is  a  confounding  of  fundamental 
categories  and  a  denial  of  an  indispensable  postulate  of  the  practi- 
cal intelligence,  to  speak  of  the  "object"  of  such  knowledge — the 
matters  of  fact  concerning  which  it  informs  us — as  exclusively 
"prospective,"  or  even  as  present.  (6)  Yet  the  bygone  must  in 
some  way  be  "recovered,"  i.e.,  brought  into  the  field  of  present 
thought,  if  it  is  to  serve  as  a  guide  for  further  inquiry  or  for  future 

"  Creative  Intelligence,  p.  14 ;  already  cited,  E.  C.  B.,  p.  53. 


TIME,  MEANING  AND  TRANSCENDENCE  541 

action.  Its  characters  and  their  relations,  or  such  of  them  as  are 
pertinent  to  the  contemplated  "invasion  of  the  future,"  must  be 
actually  before  the  agent  here  and  now,  to  be  reviewed  and  ana- 
lyzed, (c)  The  recovery  of  these,  however,  is  "imaginative,"  not 
literal  or  physical.  As  physical  existents  the  bygone  things  remain 
forever  irrecoverable.  Memory  does  not  raise  the  dead  nor  history 
rebuild  Babylon.  It  is  in  some  realm  or  order  other  than  that  of 
present  physical  objects  that  the  recovered  characters  of  the  by- 
gone have  their  present  being — in  the  realm,  namely,  of  "images." 
(d)  Since  the  things  which  are  the  objects  of  our  backward-looking 
knowledge  are  bygone  and  since  some  of  them,  at  least,  were  when 
existent,  physical,  while  the  things  in  which  we  now  believe  our- 
selves able  to  read  off  their  characters  and  relations  are  present 
and  imaginal,  these  two  classes  of  things  can  not  be  called  existen- 
tially  one.  In  any  true  inventory  of  the  concrete  particulars  in 
the  universe,  they  would  constitute  distinct  items. 

These  four  truths  of  common  sense  do  not,  of  course,  give  us 
an  exhaustive  theory  even  of  intertemporal  knowledge.  Yet  they 
set  one  upon  the  way  to  it,  and  they  embody  the  primary  facts  or 
necessary  presuppositions  to  which  any  such  theory,  and  any  ra- 
tional logic  of  practice,  must  conform.  If,  then,  Professor  Dewey 
will  but  reflect  seriously  upon  the  implications  of  this  true  saying 
of  his  own,  he  will,  I  can  not  but  think,  find  reason  for  accepting 
all  the  conclusions  which  in  his  recent  papers  he  has  the  air  of  de- 
nying: viz.,  that  we  make  judgments  which  truly  "mean"  the  past 
and  not  merely  the  "prospective";  that  consequently  epistemologi- 
cal  dualism — the  doctrine  that  the  present  content  of  a  cognitive 
experience  and  the  absent  object  "meant"  by  that  experience  are 
two  entities,  not  one — is  unescapable ;  that  the  present  content,  if  it 
is  to  function  as  a  practically  serviceable  means  of  information 
about  absent  objects,  must  in  some  degree  reproduce  the  characters 
or  relation-patterns  of  those  objects;  that  it  is  necessary  to  "admit 
the  psychical  or  mental  as  a  term  in  the  judging  process";  and 
that,  since  the  present  means  of  learning  the  characters  of  the  past 
or  other  absent  object  is  indirect,  the  general  validity  of  that  means 
can  not  be  verified  in  immediate  experience,  but  can  only  be  postu- 
lated, as  a  thing  necessary  to  be  believed  if  we  are,  in  the  present, 
to  employ  intelligence  for  the  shaping  of  the  future. 

ARTHUR  O.  LOVE  JOT. 
JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY. 


542  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Till:  PREDICATE  TERM 

IN  a  former  paper  >  I  argued  that,  since  the  partial  inverse  of  the 
A  proposition  is  valid,  the  doctrine  of  the  distribution  of  the 
predicate  breaks  down.  The  partial  inverse,  Some  non-8  is  not  P, 
contains  a  distributed  term,  P,  which  is  undistributed  in  the 
proposition,  All  8  is  P,  from  which  the  partial  inverse  is  derived. 
According  to  the  advocates  of  the  distribution  of  the  predicate,  when 
the  O  proposition  is  converted  or  the  conclusion,  Some  8  is  not  P, 
is  drawn  from  the  premises,  All  M  is  P,  Some  8  is  not  M,  the  result 
is  invalid ;  and  the  reason  they  assign  for  the  invalidity  of  the  con- 
verse and  the  conclusion  is  that  the  term  in  the  predicate  is  distrib- 
uted, whereas  it  is  undistributed  in  the  convertend  and  the  major 
premise.  My  contention,  in  brief,  is  this:  If  that  reason  invalidates 
the  converse  or  the  conclusion,  it  must  also  invalidate  the  partial 
inverse  of  A ;  but  it  is  admitted  that  it  does  not  invalidate  the  partial 
inverse  of  A ;  therefore  it  does  not  invalidate  the  converse  or  the 
conclusion. 

In  an  article  which  was  recently  published  in  this  JOURNAL*  Dr. 
Hammond  discusses  my  paper,  but  he  adduces  no  argument  which  in 
any  way  affects  the  justice  of  the  foregoing  contention.  He  occupies 
himself  in  showing  by  a  process  distinct  from  the  ordinary  one  that 
the  partial  inverse  of  A  is  valid  and  that  in  this  partial  inverse  P 
must  be  distributed  with  reference  to  non-S.  Again,  he  says  (p.  128) : 
"The  formal  violation  of  the  rule  as  to  distribution  is  apparent  in 
one  case  only.  .  .  .  The  partial  inverse  of  A  is  the  only  case  in  which 
an  originally  undistributed  term  reappears  distributed."  This  is 
exactly  what  I  maintained  in  my  paper.  I  there  said :  ' '  The  partial 
inverse  of  the  A  proposition  violates  this  rule  [as  to  distribution] 
and  yet  it  is  valid."  But  then  I  continued:  "I  infer  from  this 
that  the  doctrine  of  the  distribution  of  the  predicate  breaks  down" 
(p.  322).  Dr.  Hammond  does  not  himself  draw  this  inference,  but 
neither  on  the  other  hand  does  he  advance  any  reason  to  show  that 
it  is  unwarranted.  I  do  not  wish  to  misinterpret  Dr.  Hammond.  It 
may  be  that  by  the  word  "apparent"  in  the  passage  I  have  quoted 
he  means  that  the  formal  violation  of  the  rule  as  to  distribution  is 
merely  apparent  and  not  real.  If  this  is  his  meaning,  he  gives  no 
proof  that  it  is  not  real. 

The  following  quotation  contains  a  summary  of  his  argument: 
"The  assumption  of  the  existence  of  the  contradictory  of  the  original 
predicate  validates  the  partial  inverse :  not  that  we  manufacture  any 
promise  therefrom,  but  that,  if  that  contradictory  exist,  the  term  by 

»  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XVIII,  pp.  320-326. 
«  Vol.  XIX,  pp.  124-137. 


THE  PREDICATE  TERM  543 

its  very  nature  will  always  be  distributed  with  regard  to  it ;  and  that 
obviously  in  the  A  proposition  with  which  we  start,  if  the  contra- 
dictory of  the  predicate  exist,  then  the  subject  must  have  a  contra- 
dictory which  in  some  part  must  coincide  with  the  contradictory  of 
the  predicate ;  and  with  regard  to  that  part  the  predicate  will  always 
be  distributed.  .  .  .  The  case,  then,  in  the  matter  of  the  partial  in- 
verse is  this.    The  explanation  does  not  lie  in  any  premise,  but  does 
lie  in  the  assumption  of  the  existence  of  the  contradictory  of  the 
original  predicate.    For  if  that  contradictory  exist,  then  the  predi- 
cate, being  always  distributed  with  regard  to  it,  must  also  be  dis- 
tributed with  regard  to  whatever  portion  of  the  contradictory  of 
the  original  subject  coincides  with  it;  and  somewhere  within  the 
same  universe  these  two  infinites  must  at  least  partially  coincide. 
We  have  thus  the  right  to  say  Some  not-8  is  not  P,  since  P  must  be 
distributed  with  regard  to  some  portion  of  not-8"  (p.  127). 
This  passage  suggests  the  following  remarks : 
First :    The  utmost  that  is  achieved  by  Dr.  Hammond 's  argument 
is  that  P  must  be  distributed  with  regard  to  not-8,  and  hence  that 
we  have  a  right)  to  say  Some  not-8  is  not  P.    It  does  not  touch,  even 
remotely,  the  question  whether  there  is  not  in  the  partial  inverse  a 
formal  violation  of  the  rule  as  to  distribution.    If  Dr.  Hammond's 
argument  constitutes  a  separate  proof  of  the  validity  of  the  partial 
inverse  it  also  constitutes  a  separate  proof  of  the  correctness  of  my 
contention  that  the  doctrine  of  the  distribution  of  the  predicate 
breaks  down;  for  my  contention  is  based  upon  the  fact  that  the 
partial  inverse  of  A  is  valid,  that  P  must  be  distributed  with  regard 
to  non-S. 

Secondly :  If  in  the  case  of  any  concrete  A  proposition  inversion 
is  impossible,  this  is  never  due  to  the  fact  that  P  is  distributed  in 
the  partial  inverse.  The  partial  inverse  of  A  is  never  invalid  unless 
the  full  inverse,  Some  non-S  is  non-P,  is  invalid,  and  there  is  no 
distributed  P  in  the  full  inverse.  In  fact,  in  the  process  of  inverting 
A  the  full  inverse  is  obtained  before  the  partial  inverse ;  and  if  the 
partial  inverse  is  in  any  instance  invalid,  this  is  because  it  is  validly 
derived  from  an  invalid  full  inverse. 

Thirdly :  The  partial  inverse  of  A  is  much  more  fortunately  cir- 
cumstanced than  the  converse.  It  is  an  exceedingly  rare  occurrence 
to  find  an  A  proposition  which  can  not  be  inverted;  but  the  A 
propositions  which  can  not  be  converted  meet  us  at  every  turn.  Even 
the  example  offered  by  Dr.  Keynes  as  incapable  of  inversion,  namely, 
All  human  actions  are  foreseen  by  the  Deity,  admits  of  a  true  and 
valid  partial  inverse.  The  Deity  does  not  foresee  Himself.  Hence 
we  are  warranted  in  inferring  Something  not  a  human  action  is  not 


544  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

foreseen  by  the  Deity.  The  example  should  have  read  All  human 
actions  are  known  to  the  Deity.  Moreover,  it  is  notorious  how  com- 
mon are  the  E  propositions  which  can  not  be  converted  or  inverted. 
Consequently,  any  argument  directed  against  the  inversion  of  A  on 
the  score  that  some  A  propositions  can  not  be  inverted  will  tell  with 
indefinitely  greater  force  against  the  conversion  of  A  and  E.  It 
should  be  observed  in  addition  that,  if  a  single  invalid  inverse  be 
deemed  sufficient  to  condemn  the  process  of  inversion,  then  conver- 
sion and  obversion  must  also  be  condemned  if  in  a  single  instance 
they  issue  in  an  invalid  proposition.  The  only  A  propositions  which 
can  not  be  inverted  are  those  in  which  the  predicate  is  a  term  which 
extends  to  everything  whatsoever — such  as  "entity"  or  one  of  its 
synonyms.  This  is  the  only  kind  of  term  that  does  not  imply  a  con- 
tradictory from  which  it  is  distinct.  All  other  terms  have  it  as  their 
very  function  to  mark  off  their  object  from  other  objects. 

Fourthly:  Dr.  Hammond  says:  "The  assumption  of  the  exist- 
ence of  the  contradictory  of  the  original  predicate  validates  the 
partial  inverse. "  It  is  just  as  true  to  say :  ' '  The  assumption  of  the 
existence  of  the  original  subject  validates  the  converse  of  A."  These 
statements  are  equivalent  to  the  following:  ''All  8  is  P  can  not  be 
inverted  unless  we  assume  Some  things  are  non-P,  and  it  can  not  be 
converted  unless  we  assume  Some  things  are  S."  As  they  stand,  both 
statements  are  open  to  serious  misinterpretation.  The  accurate 
wording  would  be:  "All  8  is  P  can  not  be  inverted  unless  (we  as- 
sume that)  it  implies  Some  things  are  non-P,  and  it  can  not  be  con- 
verted unless  (we  assume  that)  it  implies  Some  things  are  S."  If 
All  S  is  P  does  not  imply  Some  things  are  non-P,  the  mere  assump- 
tion that  Some  things  are  non-P  will  not  help  us  to  invert  All  S  is  P. 
Thus,  the  proposition,  Every  tree  is  an  entity,  does  not  imply  Some 
things  are  nonentities,  and  therefore  it  can  not  be  inverted,  no  matter 
what  assumption  be  made.  It  should  also  be  remarked  that,  if  A  and 
E  be  interpreted  as  implying  the  existence  of  their  subject,  the  ex- 
ample we  have  just  mentioned  can  not  be  contraposited ;  for  "non- 
entity" would  be  the  subject  of  both  the  partial  and  the  full  contra- 
positive. 

It  must  be  remembered  that  logic  has  to  start  with  concrete  ex- 
amples. Without  an  initial  knowledge  of  concrete  examples  symbols 
are  unintelligible.  We  can  only  know  that  Some  P  is  S  is  the  con- 
verse of  All  S  is  P  because  this  is  true  of  the  concrete  examples  with 
which  we  started.  We  know  by  experience  that  many  A  propositions 
imply  the  existence  of  their  subject,  and  therefore  they  can  be  con- 
verted. We  also  know  that  nearly  all  A  propositions  imply  the 
existence  of  the  contradictory  of  their  predicate,  and  therefore  they 


THE  PREDICATE  TERM  545 

can  be  inverted.  But  we  let  All  8  is  P  stand  for  all  universal  af- 
firmative propositions  whatever,  regardless  of  the  question  whether 
they  can  be  converted  or  inverted.  This  has  been  the  main  factor 
in  creating  the  problem  of  the  existential  import  of  propositions. 
Dr.  Keynes  has  truly  said :  ' '  Strictly  speaking,  a  symbolic  expres- 
sion, such  as  All  8  is  P,  is  to  be  regarded  as  a  prepositional  form, 
rather  than  as  a  proposition  per  se.  For  it  can  not  be  described  as 
in  itself  either  true  or  false. ' ' 3  Accordingly,  logicians  have  been 
led  to  inquire  how  eduction  and  the  doctrine  of  opposition  would 
be  affected  when  the  terms  of  the  various  propositions  were  inter- 
preted as  implying  now  one  thing,  now  another.  But  in  practically 
every  case  the  result  of  the  discussion  is  determined  by  what  the 
terms  of  the  proposition  are  interpreted  to  imply,  not  by  something 
which  is  assumed  independently  of  the  proposition.  The  following 
quotation  from  Dr.  Keynes  is  pertinent  to  what  has  just  been  said. 
On  pages  223  and  228  he  deals  with  the  propositions  under  the  fol- 
lowing supposition :  ' '  Let  every  proposition  be  understood  to  imply 
the  existence  of  both  its  subject  and  its  predicate  and  also  of  their 
contradictories. ' '  And  then  on  page  228  he  adds  this  footnote :  "It 
would  be  quite  a  different  problem  if  we  were  to  assume  the  existence 
of  8  and  P  independently  of  the  affirmation  of  the  given  proposition. 
A  failure  to  distinguish  between  these  problems  is  probably  responsi- 
ble for  a  good  deal  of  the  confusion  and  misunderstanding  that  has 
arisen  in  connection  with  the  present  discussion.  But  it  is  clearly 
one  thing  to  say  (a-)  'All  8  is  P  and  8  is  assumed  to  exist,'  and 
another  thing  to  say  (&)  'All  8  is  P/  meaning  thereby  '8  exists  and 
is  always  P.'  In  case  (a)  it  is  futile  to  go  on  to  make  the  supposition 
that  8  is  non-existent;  in  case  (&),  on  the  other  hand,  there  is  nothing 
to  prevent  our  making  the  supposition,  and  we  find  that,  if  it  holds 
good,  the  given  proposition  is  false." 

One  further  observation  suggests  itself  in  connection  with  the 
partial  inverse  of  A.  In  my  last  paper  I  pointed  out  that  the  O 
proposition  gives  no  information  whatever,  even  by  implication,  about 
its  predicate.  This  has  a  very  vital  bearing  on  the  doctrine  of  the 
distribution  of  the  predicate.  The  following  question  demands  a 
distinct  answer  in  the  affirmative  or  the  negative :  Does  a  distributed 
predicate  term  give  information  about  more  individuals  in  the  ex- 
tension of  the  term  than  does  an  undistributed  predicate  term?  If 
this  question  is  answered  in  the  affirmative,  the  partial  inverse  of 
A  is  invalid,  in  spite  of  whatever  device  we  may  employ  to  justify 
it ;  and  if  it  is  invalid,  conversion  and  obversion  are  illicit  processes. 
If  the  question  is  answered  in  the  negative,  then  it  is  obviously  in- 
3  Formal  Logic,  4th  ed.,  p.  53. 


546  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

adequate  and  misleading  to  pronounce  a  given  conclusion  in  0  invalid 
on  the  sole  ground  that  its  predicate  is  distributed.  Why  shouldn't 
it  be  distributed,  if  the  mere  fact  of  its  being  distributed  conveys 
no  information  about  it?  If  the  conclusion  in  O  is  declared  to  be  in- 
valid on  some  other  ground  than  the  fact  that  the  predicate  is  distrib- 
uted, that  is  a  different  matter  altogether.  But  is  it  not  unusual  for 
a  work  on  logic  to  indicate  any  other  reason  when  it  sets  about  prov- 
ing the  rules  of  the  categorical  syllogism  and  determining  the  moods 
of  the  four  figures  f  Consider  the  following  argument :  All  M  is  P, 
Some  8  is  not  M,  therefore  Some  8  is  not  P.  It  must  be  remembered 
that  all  A  propositions,  with  hardly  an  exception,  imply  Some  things 
are  not  P.  If  this  implication  validates  the  partial  inverse,  Some 
non-8  is  not  P,  why  does  it  not  validate  the  conclusion,  Some  S  is  not 
Pt  It  is  plainly  no  answer  to  say  that  P  is  distributed  in  Some  8 
is  not  P. 

Dr.  Hammond  takes  exception  to  an  expression  which  occurred  in 
my  argument  against  the  class  mode  of  interpreting  the  categorical 
proposition.  Since  he  does  not  expressly  dispute  the  point  I  was 
there  making,  there  might  seem  to  be  little  use  in  discussing  his  ob- 
jection. But  his  criticism  tends  to  obscure  the  issue  of  my  argument 
and  therefore  calls  for  a  word  of  comment.  His  general  theory  as 
to  the  distributive  and  collective  use  of  terms  need  not  engage  us 
here.  He  seems  to  hold  that  only  collective  terms  can  be  used  col- 
lectively. He  says  that  in  the  proposition,  Any  regiment  is  made 
up  of  soldiers,  "regiment"  is  used  collectively  and  is  distributed.  I 
had  thought  that  a  term  must  be  used  distributively  in  order  to  be 
distributed.  Since  the  predicate  "made  up  of  soldiers"  is  asserted 
of  every  regiment,  that  is,  of  all  regiments  taken  one  by  one,  I  should 
think  that  the  subject  "regiment"  is  used  distributively.  In  the 
proposition,  The  American  regiments  won  the  victory,  I  should  say 
that  "the  American  regiments"  is  used  collectively,  because  the 
predicate  "won  the  victory"  is  not  asserted  of  the  American  regi- 
ments taken  one  by  one.  Take  the  propositions,  The  pupils  of  the 
class  are  boys,  The  pupils  of  the  class  weigh  three  tons.  In  the  first 
proposition  I  should  consider  that  "the  pupils  of  the  class"  is  used 
distributively  and  that  the  subject  is  distributed;  in  the  second, 
that  "the  pupils  of  the  class"  is  used  collectively  and  that  the 
subject  is  a  singular  term.  But,  as  I  said,  there  is  no  need  to  discuss 
Dr.  Hammond's  general  theory.  In  my  paper  I  had  written:  "In 
the  proposition,  All  the  angles  of  a  triangle  are  equal  to  two  right 
angles,  no  logician  would  speak  of  the  subject  term,  'angle  of  a  tri- 
angle,' as  either  distributed  or  undistributed."  Dr.  Hammond  says 
that  the  subject  is  not  "angle  of  a  triangle,"  but  "all  the  angles  of 


THE  PREDICATE  TERM  547 

a  triangle."  If  the  example  'be  taken  out  of  its  context,  there  may 
be  something  to  be  said  for  Dr.  Hammond's  view;  but  considered 
in  its  context  and  in  relation  to  the  point  it  was  intended  to  illustrate, 
there  was  a  special  appropriateness  in  speaking  of  "angle  of  a  tri- 
angle" as  the  subject.  I  was  arguing  against  the  class  mode  of 
reading  categorical  propositions  and  I  used  this  example  to  illustrate 
the  incorrectness  of  reading  the  propositions  in  that  way.  On  the 
class  interpretation  of  propositions  the  subject  in  All  men  are  ani- 
mals stands  for  a  class,  that  is,  for  a  collection,  and  this  collection  is 
affirmed  to  be  included  in  another  collection.  In  spite  of  this,  the 
subject  is  said  to  be  "man,"  not  "all  men."  And  yet  unless  "all 
men"  be  taken  together  as  a  collection  (i.e.,  collectively),  and  not  one 
by  one  (i.e.,  distributively),  the  class  mode  of  reading  the  proposition 
is  not  employed  at  all.  The  point  I  was  endeavoring  to  make  was 
this,  that  if  the  logician  interpreted  the  subject  and  predicate  of 
that  proposition  as  classes,  he  had  no  more  right  to  call  "man"  the 
distributed  subject  than  he  had  to  call  "angle  of  a  triangle"  the 
distributed  subject  of  All  the  angles  of  a  triangle  are  equal  to  two 
right  angles. 

The  point  which  has  just  been  discussed  suggests  another  remark. 
When  the  logician  borrows  a  term  from  common  language  because 
its  meaning  renders  it  suitable  to  a  given  purpose,  he  should  hesitate 
to  employ  it  in  such  a  way  that  its  original  meaning  is  lost. 
Dr.  Hammond  says:  "If  the  term  be  singular,  then  in  any  asser- 
tion made  of  it  it  will  be  distributed,  even  though  it  have  no  exten- 
sion in  the  sense  of  component  species,  since  the  assertion  is  taken 
as  true  of  the  only  instance  of  the  term  there  is"  (p.  134).  Now,  of 
course,  no  fault  can  be  found  with  Dr.  Hammond  personally  for 
holding  this  opinion,  since  it  is  shared  by  others.  But  it  is  obvious 
that ' '  distributed ' '  has  been  emptied  of  all  its  original  meaning  when 
it  is  applied  to  a  term  which  refers  to  a  single  object.  It  is  as  if  we 
were  to  say, ' '  The  mother  distributed  the  apple  to  her  son, ' '  and  then 
were  to  defend  our  use  of  the  word  "distributed"  by  the  plea  that 
that  was  the  only  apple  the  mother  had.  It  is  bad  enough  to  speak 
of  a  singular  proposition  as  "universal"  without  calling  its  subject 
"distributed."  Over  and  above  the  inappropriateness  of  calling  a 
singular  proposition  universal,  there  is  this  further  disadvantage 
connected  with  it,  that  a  pair  of  universal  opposite  propositions  (All 
8  is  P,  No  8  is  P)  may  in  a  given  instance  be  false  together,  but 
this  is  never  the  case  with  a  pair  of  singular  opposites  (This  8  is  P, 
This  8  is  not  P).  The  universal  and  the  singular  proposition  have 
this  in  common,  that  their  subject  is  definite,  and  thus  they  serve 
the  purpose  of  securing  identity  of  reference  when  employed  along 


r,  18  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

with  another  proposition  in  a  syllogism.  Identity  of  reference  is 
the  main  consideration  in  dealing  with  the  premises  of  the  categori- 
cal syllogism,  and  if  a  terminology  could  be  invented  which  should 
set  this  forth  simply  and  unambiguously  and  which  should  be  uni- 
versally applicable,  it  would  be  a  distinct  gain  to  logic.  As  it  is, 
separate  provision  has  commonly  to  be  made  for  arguments  like 
the  following :  Most  M  is  P,  Most  M  is  8,  therefore  Some  8  is  P.  "We 
may,  however,  construct  dicta  for  the  third  figure  which  will  cover 
every  possible  syllogism  in  that  figure;  thus:  1.  //  [every  M  or] 
some  M  is  both  8  and  P,  then  some  8  is  P.  2.  //  {every  M  or]  some 
M  is  8  and  not  P,  then  some  8  w  not  P.  "Every  M "  is  enclosed  in 
brackets  because  the  dicta  are  really  complete  without  it.  The  first 
dictum  provides  for  the  moods  Darapti,  Disamis,  and  Datisi;  the 
second  provides  for  Felapton,  Bocardo,  and  Ferison;  and  the  two 
together  provide  for  every  possible  mood  in  the  third  figure,  whatever 
be  the  sign  of  quantity  which  is  employed.  Moreover,  they  give  us 
the  three  rules  which  are  required  to  justify  any  combination  of  prem- 
ises in  the  third  figure,  namely:  1.  The  subjects  of  the  premises 
must  overlap.  2.  The  minor  premise  must  be  affirmative.  3.  The 
conclusion  must  be  particular. 

In  the  concluding  paragraph  of  his  article  Dr.  Hammond  quotes 
me  as  follows :  ' '  The  use  of  the  doctrine  of  the  distribution  of  the 
predicate  involves  a  vicious  circle.  .  .  .  The  logician  .  .  .  first  calls 
upon  the  student's  knowledge  of  the  implication  of  propositions  to 
prove  the  doctrine,  and  then  he  bids  the  student  call  upon  his  knowl- 
edge of  the  doctrine  in  order  to  find  out  the  implication."  Dr. 
Hammond  claims  that  this  objection  "involves  final  questions  of  the 
nature  of  logic."  I  do  not  understand  how  the  objection  can  involve 
such  questions  unless  the  doctrine  of  the  distribution  of  the  predicate 
is  so  deeply  imbedded  in  the  substance  of  logical  theory  that  there 
can  not  be  a  science  of  Logic  without  it.  Surely  no  one  would  main- 
tain that  this  doctrine  is  absolutely  essential  to  Logic.  But  perhaps  I 
have  misunderstood  the  drift  of  Dr.  Hammond's  remark.  The  point 
is  touched  upon  very  briefly  in  his  article ;  and  it  would  be  unprofit- 
able to  continue  a  discussion  which,  after  all,  may  be  based  upon  a 
misunderstanding. 

JOHN  J.  TOOHEY. 

GEORGETOWN  UNIVERSITY. 


BEHAVIORISM  549 

BEHAVIORISM  AND  THE  PROGRAMME  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  peculiar  value  of  a  behavioristic  approach  to  the  problem  of 
knowledge  is  that  it  renders  possible  a  definitely  factual  method 
of  treatment.  Knowledge,  of  course,  consists  of  propositions  or 
judgments.  But  judgments  are  not  ultimate  entities,  and  unless  we 
are  able  to  push  back  to  the  conditions  under  which  they  arise,  our 
theory  of  knowledge  can  not  be  on  a  secure  foundation.  Judgments 
are  essentially  reactions,  and  they  arise  only  in  the  context  of  highly 
developed  organic  life.  Furthermore,  the  possession  of  meaning  is 
the  distinctive  mark  of  judgment.  Thus  our  problem  may  be  formu- 
lated as  follows:  Under  what  conditions  is  it  possible  to  have  reac- 
tions which  possess  meaning?  We  may  think  of  epistemology  as 
dealing  with  the  laws  exhibited  by  such  entities.  In  order  to  make 
this  conception  clearer,  I  shall  go  on  to  apply  it  to  three  fundamental 
questions,  namely,  the  lower  limit  of  judgment,  the  functioning  of 
the  universal  in  behavior,  and  the  nature  of  truth. 

First,  then,  let  us  consider  the  lower  limit  of  judgment.  Here  we 
are  face  to  face  with  the  double  requirement  that  every  judgment  shall 
be  regarded  as  a  reaction  and  that  every  judgment  shall  mean  some- 
thing or  symbolize  something.  Now  since  every  response  ex  hypothesi 
is  occasioned  by  a  stimulus  it  might  appear  that  in  a  sense  every 
response  must  be  regarded  as  standing  for  or  meaning  something 
other  than  itself,  i.e.,  its  stimulus.  This,  however,  would  be  a  serious 
confusion.  If  we  are  asking  why  such  and  such  a  judgment  in  fact 
comes  to  be  made — that  is,  if  we  enquire  as  to  its  efficient  cause — we 
must  always  trace  it  back  to  some  specific,  direct  nexus  of  stimulus 
and  response.  But  this  causal  relation  of  stimulus  and  response 
which  must  be  present  in  the  history  of  all  judgments  can  not  be 
treated  as  equivalent  to  the  relation  of  the  judgment  to  its  denota- 
tion. A  judgment  may  mean  something  in  the  future,  or  something 
non-existent,  or  it  may  be  a  universal  or  it  may  be  false,  and  in  such 
cases  its  denotation  obviously  can  not  be  its  cause. 

Nevertheless  we  must  still  deal  with  the  relation  between  judg- 
ment and  denotation,  between  symbol  and  object,  in  terms  of  stim- 
ulus and  response.  When  we  say  that  a  judgment  stands  for  an 
object,  we  can  only  mean  that  it  is  the  effective  equivalent  of  that 
object  in  behavior.  If  the  object  itself  were  present  as  stimulus  it 
would  modify  behavior  in  a  determinate  respect.  We  may  say  that 
a  judgment  symbolizes  this  object  when  its  presence  as  stimulus  in 
the  absence,  usually,  of  the  object,  modifies  behavior  in  the  same 
respect,  as  would  the  present  object,  within  certain  limits.  I  say 


550  JOURNAL  OF 

within  certain  limits  because  the  effect  of  a  symbol  is  likely  to  differ 
considerably,  though  in  no  merely  arbitrary  manner,  from  the  effect 
of  the  object.  It  is  one  thing  to  read  a  sign  to  the  effect  that  tres- 
passers will  be  prosecuted,  and  a  very  different  matter  to  be  haled 
before  the  law. 

Here,  however,  we  have  obtained  a  clue  to  the  lower  limit  of 
judgment.  Judgment,  or  the  significant  use  of  symbols,  is  possible 
only  where  reactions  have  become  so  refined  and  so  highly  individ- 
ualized that  they  maintain  an  identity  and  possess  an  intrinsic  inter- 
est which  makes  them  serviceable  as  stimuli,  quite  apart  from  the 
stimuli  which  occasion  them.  When  a  dog  digs  frantically  we  must 
not  say  that  he  judges  that  there  is  a  rabbit  near  by,  for  his  reac- 
tion can  not  be  dissociated  from  its  occasioning  cause.  It  possesses  no 
special  and  separate  interest  and  individuality  of  its  own.  But  if 
a  man  says  "There  is  a  rabbit  in  that  hole"  we  have  a  unique  reac- 
tion which  can  be  sharply  and  if  necesary  permanently  distin- 
guished from  raillons  of  others  and  so  is  eminently  fitted  to  serve 
as  a  symbol  or  cue  to  specific  action.  Judgment,  then,  depends 
wholly  on  the  capacity  to  produce  reactions  which  can  serve  as 
symbols,  reactions  as  distinctive,  as  varied,  and  as  unmistakable  as 
the  innumerable  physical  objects  for  which  they  stand.  Now  this 
capacity  presumably  depends  to  some  degree,  perhaps  to  a  very  con- 
siderable degree,  upon  cerebral  development.  A  dog  with  a  human 
brain  might  conceivably  invent  a  system  of  conventional  signs, 
though  with  the  canine  organs  of  response  these  could  hardly  be  very 
adequate.  All  this,  however,  is  more  or  less  speculative.  What  is 
quite  certain  is  that  the  capacity  to  produce  reactions  well  adapted 
for  serving  as  judgments  depends  most  importantly  upon  the  action 
system.  As  John  B.  Watson  points  out,  the  vocal  mechanism  with 
all  its  exquisite  delicacy  is  a  very  distinctive  organ  of  human  intelli- 
gence and  most,  if  not  all  thinking  can  actually  be  reduced  to  laryn- 
geal  work.  The  reasonable  conclusion  seems  to  be  that  given  the 
world  of  organic  life  as  we  actually  know  it,  only  those  individuals 
physically  equipped  for  true  speech  can  make  judgments  or  possess 
knowledge  in  the  proper  sense  of  the  word.  It  should  be  noted  that 
this  does  not  rule  out  gestures,  such  as  pointing  in  reply  to  a  ques- 
tion, from  the  category  of  judgments.  But  I  would  maintain  that 
such  bodily  movements  only  acquire  the  force  of  conventional  symbols, 
that  is,  judgments  in  beings  already  schooled  to  the  use  of  language 
reactions  proper.  Language  behavior  alone  seems  to  possess  the 
subtlety  and  be  capable  of  the  uniqueness  to  be  the  adequate  instru- 
ment of  a  symbolism. 


BEHAVIORISM  551 

I  turn  now  to  the  second  problem  mentioned  above,  that  of  the 
functioning  of  the  universal.  We  have  already  seen  that  when  a 
symbol  occurs  as  stimulus  it  may  modify  behavior  less  dramatically 
than  would  the  presence  of  the  object  for  which  it  stands.  Some- 
times, to  be  sure,  this  is  not  the  case.  If  I  hear  a  sudden  shout  of 
"There's  an  automobile  behind  you!"  my  reaction  is  likely  to  be 
just  as  decisive  as  if  I  had  seen  it.  If,  however,  some  one  tells  me  that 
ultimately  I  shall  die  I  do  not  immediately  take  tearful  farewells  of 
all  my  friends,  deliver  myself  of  deathbed  sentiments,  and  generally 
act  as  though  in  articulo  mortis.  The  furthest  I  am  likely  to  go  is 
into  a  fit  of  philosophic  pessimism  and  a  resolve  to  make  my  will. 
Once  more,  if  I  am  told  that  the  returned  soldiers  ought  to  be  taken 
care  of  in  the  reconstruction,  my  response  is  likely  to  be  no  more  than 
a  somewhat  vague  assent  unless  it  is  my  misfortune  to  be  a  politician 
and  liable  to  be  confronted  with  large  bodies  of  angry  veterans  at 
short  notice. 

Now  the  essential  difference  between  these  three  cases  is  that 
they  exhibit  progressively  increasing  generalization.  The  relation 
of  symbol  and  object  in  the  first  instance  is  simple.  The  sight 
of  the  oncoming  automobile  inspires  the  saving  shout,  and  it  is 
this  immediate  relationship  which  makes  the  shout  so  very  effective 
a  symbol  for  the  vehicle.  In  the  other  two  instances  the  nexus  be- 
tween symbol  and  object  is  much  more  complicated.  Here  the  judg- 
ments are  the  results  of  long  and  highly  elaborate  social  experience, 
that  is,  many  people  have  been  concerned  in  making  them.  Thus  the 
peculiar  value  of  language  reactions  is  that  they  enable  us  to  take 
advantage  of  wide  areas  of  experience,  and  furthermore  to  adjust 
ourselves  more  wisely  though  less  dramatically  to  a  more  inclusive 
environment  than  would  otherwise  be  possible.  Events  remote  in 
time  and  place  play  an  effective  part  in  life,  and  we  are  able  to  adjust 
ourselves  adequately  to  distant  facts  and  to  benefit  by  abstractions 
and  analyses  of  indefinite  complexity.  Hence  the  theory  of  univer- 
sals  as  envisaged  in  behavioristic  terms  must  show  first  how  universal 
assertions  actually  build  up  as  responses  to  stimulation,  and  second 
how  they  function  in  connecting  present  behavior  with  remote  or 
unapproachable  facts. 

Elsewhere  I  have  dealt  with  the  truth  problem  from  this  point 
of  view.1  What  we  obtain  is  in  effect  a  correspondence  theory  of 
truth,  but  we  are  able  to  avoid  the  central  difficulty  of  the  traditional 
correspondence  theory  since  our  concept  of  the  behavior  mechanism 
provides  us  with  an  agency  which  links  up  judgments  with  their 

i" Truth  as  Correspondence:  a  Re-definition,"  thia  JOUKNAL,  Vol.  XIX, 
No.  7. 


552  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

objects.  If  we  ask  why  a  judgment  stands  for  a  certain  object,  our 
reply  will  be  that  somewhere  or  under  some  conditions  judgment  and 
object  are  related  as  response  and  stimulus.  If  we  try  to  confine 
ourselves  to  propositions  or  objectives  by  themselves,  and  systemati- 
cally refuse  to  treat  them  as  elements  in  actual  causal  sequences,  the 
above  question  can  not  be  answered,  and  consequently  the  whole 
account  of  truth  in  terms  of  correspondence  has  to  be  given  up. 

II 

Much  more  briefly  I  will  now  try  to  suggest  how  a  philosophy 
operating  with  behavioristic  concepts  can  approach  the  problems 
of  conduct.  Here  we  find  ourselves  committed  to  what  in  effect  is 
nothing  less  than  an  ethic  of  self-realization.  Given  a  complex  and 
subtle  behavior  mechanism,  which  is  surely  an  individual  in  the 
fullest  sense  of  the  term,  the  obviously  fundamental  problem  of  life 
is  to  set  up  and  maintain  conditions  propitious  for  its  most  effective 
working.  On  the  negative  side,  this  means  that  we  must  strive  to 
build  up  habit  structures  in  the  individual  such  that  functional 
conflicts  with  their  accompanying  suppressions  and  distortions  either 
do  not  occur  or  are  reduced  to  a  minimum.  That  such  suppressions 
and  distortions  may  easily  occur  and  may  work  infinite  harm  is 
impressively  shown  by  Freudian  psychology  and  the  literature  of 
psychoanalysis  generally.  Since  functional  conflict  most  character- 
istically arises  between  habit  structures  which  are  allowed  to  develop 
in  the  individual  and  the  conventional  demands  of  society,  we  may 
look  for  a  theory  of  harmonious  relations  between  individual  and 
society  in  terms  of  the  general  concept  of  sublimation.  An  interest- 
ing point  here  is  the  status  of  genius.  Creative  genius  usually 
amounts  to  a  violent  but  only  partially  successful  effort  at  complete 
sublimation.  For  the  genius  himself,  then,  his  gift,  apart  from  any 
collateral  rewards  it  may  bring  in  the  form  of  reputation  or  money, 
is  more  or  less  a  misfortune,  as  implying  a  disharmony  and  so  a  de- 
parture from  the  ideal  of  the  good  and  happy  life.  For  society  his 
gift  is  likely  to  be  of  vast  value  in  that  it  tends  to  improve  the  social 
medium  and  thus  make  successful  adjustments  easier  for  others. 
Then,  on  the  positive  side,  our  world-view  demands  that  we  look  for 
such  a  development  of  the  individual  as  will  adjust  his  desires  and 
needs  so  that  all  of  them  can  come  to  maximum  satisfaction.  To 
sum  up  the  whole  matter,  we  begin  with  the  concept  of  concrete 
personality,  which  is  precisely  what  the  behavior  mechanism  amounts 
to,  and  our  theory  of  life  naturally  requires  the  conservation  and 
development  of  personality  to  the  highest  possible  degree  of  effective- 
ness. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  553 

Evidently  such  a  program  will  result  in  one  thing  only,  a  philos- 
ophy in  the  legitimate  and  historical  sense  of  the  word.  Our  method, 
to  be  sure,  will  be  that  of  science — that  is  to  say,  logical  analysis — 
but  only  because  this  is  the  only  possible  mode  of  discursive  thought. 
And  our  terms  will  all  be  ponderable  entities  with  which  science  can 
and  does  deal.  But  our  questions  will  not  be  those  of  any  science. 
We  ask  how  knowledge  is  possible  and  what  are  the  norms  of  the  good 
life.  And  our  replies  will  be  worked  out  in  terms  of  actual  fact, 
in  terms  of  knowledge  as  it  actually  arises  and  life  as  it  is  actually 
lived. 

JAMES  L.  MUESELL. 

LAKE  ERIE  COLLEGE. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  Meeting  of  Extremes  in  Contemporary  Philosophy.  BERNARD 
BOSANQUET.  Macmillan.  1921.  Pp.  xxviii  +  220. 
Dr.  Bosanquet's  volume,  in  spite  of  its  comparative  brevity,  is 
unusually  comprehensive  and  suggestive;  first  because  his  survey 
of  the  current  conflicting  types  of  thought  bears  the  stamp  of  his 
exceptionally  wide  knowledge  and  clear  insight,  and  further  on 
account  of  the  highly  interesting  developments  which,  in  his  opinion, 
must  mark  the  future.  "You  are  no  longer  taking  a  single  bearing 
with  a  single  compass,  but  covering  a  whole  region  with  a  systematic 
survey"  (p.  ix).  This  interest  centers — as  may  be  inferred  from 
his  title — in  something  approaching  paradox.  For  his  analysis  of 
the  present  situation  is  directed  to  show  that  the  opposed  schools 
whose  vigorous  polemics  animate  modern  speculation  share  so  much 
in  common  that  they  really  are — often  unconsciously — allies  rather 
than  antagonists,  and  the  explicit  principles  which  mark  their  di- 
vergence have  implicit  consequences  which  logically  lead  to  a  con- 
vergence that  is  still  more  fundamental;  and  thus  the  perspectives 
of  philosophy  are  completely  transformed.  This  result  springs 
mainly  from  the  rapidly  changing  character  of  philosophic  dis- 
cussion; it  is  becoming  subtler,  more  refined,  and  the  old  "bombard- 
ment at  long  ranges"  has  given  place  to  "sapping  and  mining" 
(p.  vii).  Whither  this  concealed  activity  leads  and  where  the  next 
explosion  will  occur  thus  constitute  fascinating  problems.  I  ven- 
ture to  add  that  in  my  opinion  Dr.  Bosanquet's  own  position  on 
several  fundamental  points  seems  to  be  more  clearly  expressed 
than  in  his  earlier  volumes — with  regard  to  sense-data,  the  relation 
between  existence  and  thought,  and  between  philosophy  and  religion ; 
but  this  again  is  merely  the  more  explicit  formulation  of  what  has 
always  been  implicit  in  the  author's  idealism. 


:,;,4  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOril  Y 

This  ground  of  agreement,  however,  is  to  be  found  not  in  mere 
devotion  to  truth  or  sincerity  of  conviction.  The  trenchancy  of 
the  "extremes"  is  well  illustrated  by  the  case  which  first  attracted 
the  author's  notice — "the  startling  difference  and  agreement"  be- 
tween Italian  neo-idealism,  and  the  neo-realism  of  Professor  Drake 
and  his  collaborators,  together  with  Dr.  Alexander  (p.  viii)  ;  be- 
tween the  system  for  which  "reality  is  thinking,"  and  "being"  or 
"mind"  are  "mutually  contradictory  terms,"  and  that  which  assorts 
the  non-mental  nature  of  reality.  *  It  would  be  unfair  to  summarize 
Dr.  Bosanquet's  treatment  of  the  basis  wherein  he  finds  the  identity 
of  these  antithetical  standpoints;  it  must  suffice  to  draw  attention 
to  the  degree  of  their  divergence  as  one  indication  of  the  fresh 
interest  which  his  analysis  gives  to  the  issues  involved ;  I  shall  refer 
to  an  equally  striking  instance  later. 

The  readers  of  this  JOURNAL  will  probably  be  mainly  concerned 
with  the  attitude  taken  up  by  the  writer,  as  representing  an  old 
and  established  type  of  idealism  which  has  in  recent  decades  aroused 
a  good  deal  of  vigorous  criticism,  towards  American  neo-realism.  I 
ventured  recently  to  express  the  opinion  that  nothing  "prevent* 
realism  from  taking  its  place  within  a  system  of  absolute  ideal- 
ism";2 and  it  appears  to  me  that  this  suggestion  finds  much  to 
support  it  in  Dr.  Bosanquet's  volume.  He  accords  the  fullest  recog- 
nition to  the  value  of  the  arguments  advanced  by  the  realists. 
"Speculative  philosophy  welcomes  the  assertion  that  the  world  of 
sense-perception  has  being  in  its  own  right.  .  .  .  Hegel's  and  Green's 
position  is  that  a  chair  is  a  chair  right  enough.  .  .  .  The  speculative 
philosopher  re-cognizes  as  a  comrade  the  neo-realist  who  demands  a 
place  for  all  that  sense-perception  has  to  give  us"  (pp.  2,  5,  7).* 
I  think  all  realists  will  agree  that  this,  in  connection  with  the  de- 
tailed discussion  of  the  relation  between  thought  and  existence  in 
Chap.  IV,  is  sufficiently  definite;  it  detracts,  further,  very  much 
from  the  weight  of  the  adverse  criticism  to  which  I  have  just  alluded, 
which  has  always  seemed  to  me  completely  to  ignore  the  true  ab- 
solutist standpoint  towards  these  problems.  !  Dr.  Bosanquet,  of 
course,  proceeds  to  indicate  the  difficulties  which  realism  has  to 
face;  these  may  be  best  summed  tip  in  his  statement  that  "sensa 
may  exist  per  se,  but  we  can  not  get  them  so"  (p.  13),  and  in  the 
conclusions  which  he  draws  from  this;  but  these  will  doubtless  rc- 

»  Gentile,   Theory  of  Mind  at  Pwre  Act,  pp.   66,   19.     Drake,   Etsays   in 
Critical  Bea'irm. 

*  This  JOURNAL,  March  16,  1922,  p.  157. 

*  Of.  p.  75 ;  "  the  neo-realist  .  .  .  building  the  foundations  of  that  specula- 
tive philosophy  whose  super-structure  already  exists  .  .  .  they  enrich  and  amend 
it." 


BOOK  REVIEWS  555 

ceive  due  attention  from  the  writers  most  directly  concerned ;  and  not 
the  least  interesting  of  their  comments  will  surely  be  their  reaction 
to  the  alliance  which  Dr.  Bosanquet  discerns  between  the  critical 
school  and  Mr.  Bradley  in  "the  parallel  movement  between  absolut- 
ism" and  critical  realism,  and  the  analogy  which  persists  even  be- 
yond "the.  point  at  which,  primd  facie,  they  sharply  diverge"  (pp. 
127-130).  The  divergent  principles  are,  naturally,  repudiated — 
the  critical  realist  "analysis  is  a  fundamental  error"  (p.  137)  ;  and 
I  may  be  permitted  to  express  my  pleasure  in  finding  that  Dr.  Bosan- 
quet regards  the  complete  critical  theory  as  involving  a  noumenalism 
akin  to  Kant's — a  position  that  I  have  myself  attempted  to  sub- 
stantiate,4 Thus  the  tangle  of  "isms"  presents  yet  another  "meet- 
ing of  extremes" — in  this  instance  a  "common  error,  the  confusion 
of  transcendence  of  experience  and  transcendence  of  immediacy," 
characteristic  equally  of  American  critical  realism  and  Italian  neo- 
idealism  (p.  149). 

Next  in  degree  of  interest  is  the  author's  brief  discussion  of 
the  philosophical  bearings  of  the  relativity  theory ;  here  again  I  am 
glad  to  find  that,  in  his  opinion,  "the  moral  of  relativity  is  not  the 
permeation  of  the  universe  by  mind  or  minds"  (p.  16).  This  con- 
clusion, or  one  closely  analogous  to  it,  has  undoubtedly  unduly  im- 
posed itself  upon  current  philosophic  thought,  and  been  adopted 
as  a  fresh  basis,  if  not  indeed  the  final  proof,  of  various  modes  of 
subjectivism.  Such  inferences,  in  my  opinion,  are  altogether  ground- 
less, and  Dr.  Bosanquet 's  analysis  of  the  subject  may  be  recom- 
mended to  the  many  who  desire  to  apprehend  the  real  value  of  this 
latest  Coperaican  transformation  in  scientific  theories.  The  phil- 
osophical aspects  of  the  problem  center  in  the  nature  of  space-time. 
Dr.  Bosanquet  emphasizes  the  importance  of  the  relation  between 
"our  primitive  sense  of  time"  and  "uniform  time,"  and  concludes 
that  "the  spatio-temporal  universe  (has)  no  single  space-time  of 
its  own"  (pp.  152-154).  Whether  this  is  true  or  not  appears  to 
me  to  depend  on  the.  distinction  between  the  scientific  concept  of 
the  (physical)  universe,  and  the  absolutist  (or  idealist)  conception 
of  the  Whole.  The  first  seems  to  demand  a  universal,  common,  basal 
space-time  of  which  the  varying  "relativity"  systems  are  all  sub- 
sidiary aspects  depending  upon  their  relevant  physical  conditions; 
or  as  Lord  Haldane  has  expressed  this,  "change  in  standpoint  gives 

*  "It  is  futile  to  maintain  that  [the  object  of  thought]  is  not  a  Ding-an- 
sich"  (p.  146).  Cf.  Tl\e  Monist,  July,  1922;  "The  Failure  of  Critical  Real- 
ism. ' ' 

s  The  Beign  of  Belativity,  p.  402.  I  may  refer  to  a  fuller  discussion  of 
the  subject  in  Mind,  Jan.,  1922,  p.  40. 


556  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

no  change  in  the  actual."5  If,  on  the  other  hand,  we  advance  to 
the  profounder  philosophical  distinction  "between  time  in  the  Ab- 
solute and  the  Absolute  in  time, ' ' 6  then  it  becomes  possible  to  ac- 
cept Dr.  Bosanquet's  suggestion  of  the  space-time-lessness  of  the 
Whole.7 

The  nature  of  time,  further,  presents  us  with  what  is  perhaps 
the  most  striking  of  all  "extremes" — the  connection  between  time 
itself  and  the  widest  aspects  of  ethics  and  religion.  For  time  is  an 
element  in  all  evolution  or  development;  and  hence  arises  "the  ulti- 
mate crux  of  speculation;  the  place  of  time,  progress,  and  change 
in  the  universe"  (p.  125).  In  facing  these  issues,  argues  Dr.  Bo- 
sanquet,  modern  philosophy  stands  at  a  parting  of  the  ways.  ' '  The 
sentiment  of  religion,"  to  begin  with,  "begins  in  its  own  right, 
though  it  has  an  intimate  relation,  but  one  never  passing  into 
identity,  with  morality";  this  position  provides  a  common  basis  for 
"Alexander  the  realist,  James  the  radical  empiricist,  and  Bradley 
the  absolutist"  (pp.  68,  69).  Once  more,  "our  two  extremes,  crea- 
tive thought  (Gentile)  and  creative  time  (Alexander),  meet  in  the 
demand  that  true  being  must  engage  in  progress"  (p.  158).  The 
general  standpoint  of  Italian  neo-idealism  is  subjected  to  a  searching 
criticism  which  goes  (in  my  opinion)  to  the  root  of  the  vital  issues 
involved.  "Sociality,  religion,  metaphysic,  are  forms  for  which 
the  system  can  find  no  place"  (p.  163)  ;  but  these  demand,  in  their 
own  inherent  nature  without  being  whittled  away  or  transformed, 
full  recognition  in  any  philosophy  that  merits  the  name;  they  call 
therefore  for  ' '  an  element  of  stability  as  well  as  an  element  of  altera- 
tion." As  to  where  this  stability  is  to  be  found,  the  author's  own 
position  is  perfectly  definite,  although  its  difficulty,  until  it  is  fully 
developed,  gives  it  a  superficial  quality  of  paradox.  "The  whole — 
the  universe — all  that  in  any  sense  is — can  not  change.  All  that 
is  includes  all  that  can  be."  Thus  we  have,  at  first  sight,  both  the 
"block  universe"  of  James,8  and  the  tout  est  donne  of  Bergson; 
but  for  Dr.  Bosanquet's  counter-arguments  to  these  all  too  hasty 
impeachments  of  absolutism  I  must  refer  readers  to  his  own  volume, 
restricting  myself  to  their  bearing  on  the  crucial  dichotomy  between 
religion  and  morality.  "We  must  distinguish,  to  begin  with,  "be- 
tween a  movement  within,  and  a  movement  or  change  of,  the  all, 
of  the  ultimate  foundation  of  being  as  such";9  and  this  distinction 

«  Meeting  of  Extremes,  p.  126. 

'  Cf .  Green,  Proleg.  to  Ethics,  p.  57 ;  "  neither  in  time  nor  in  space,  im- 
material and  immovable,  eternally  one  with  itself." 

• ' '  The  radical  misapprehension  of  English  idealism  which  appears  to  pre- 
vail in  recent  American  writers"  inherited  from  Royce  and  James  (p.  198). 

•  Pp.  177,  179,  182. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  557 

then  involves  the  essential  inadequacy  of  mere  moralism,  despite  the 
high  value  of  its  principles  and  aspirations  so  far  as  these  carry  us. 
' '  Man 's  perfectibility  as  realized  in  the,  unending  series  of  events  is  an 
obvious  contradiction."  In  fundamental  contrast  with  all  types  of 
such  ethicism  Dr.  Bosanquet  upholds  "a  unity  in  which  the  finite 
spirit  is  at  peace,  and  raised  above  the  moralistic  contradiction,  in 
faith  by  the  religious  attitude  and  in  speculation  by  philosophy"; 
and  the  most  fitting  conclusion  to  my  inadequate  attempt  to  present 
the  essence  of  a  rich  and  profound  philosophy  is  provided  by  the 
author's  insistence  upon  "a  total  perfection,  which  to  approach  and 
apprehend  through  the  finite  and  its  essential  nexus  with  the  in- 
finite is  the  touchstone  for  a  man,  for  life,  and  for  philosophy. ' ' 10 
It  is  to  be  hoped  that  his  book  will  further  the  better  appreciation 
of  an  idealism  that  has  too  long  been  misrepresented  and  misunder- 
stood. 

J.  E.  TURNER. 
LIVERPOOL,  ENGLAND. 

Platonism.    PAUL  ELMER  MORE.    Princeton  University  Press.    1917. 

Pp.  ix  +  307. 
The  Religion  of  Plato.    PAUL  ELMER  MORE.    Princeton  University 

Press.    1921.    Pp.  xii -j- 352. 

These  volumes  are  announced  as  the  first  two  of  a  work  having 
to  do  with  the  beginnings  and  early  environment  of  Christianity. 
The  earlier  one  is  introductory  to  the  other  four  (three  of  them 
being  not  yet  prepared),  and  of  the  second,  the  subject  is  "the  re- 
ligion of  Plato  as  part  of  the  great  spiritual  adventure  of  the  ancient 
world  from  the  death  of  Socrates  to  the  council  of  Chalcedon  just 
eight  centuries  and  a  half  later."  These  two  volumes  are  not  in- 
tended to  be  works  in  history,  and  one  infers  the  whole  work  when 
completed  will  not  be  primarily  an  historical  one.  The  introductory 
volume  is  called  by  its  author  rather  an  invitation  to  philosophy 
and  to  the  kind  of  philosophy  that  he  takes  Platonism  to  be. 

The  two  volumes  are  naturally  controlled,  to  a  great  extent,  by 

the  subject  matter  they  approach.    The  philosophy  they  invite  us  to 

practise  is  austere  and  elevated,  a  system  of  reflections  that  is  evoked 

/by  what  Mr.  More  calls  dualism  and  by  which  he  means,  I  think,  any 

I  two  elements  or  forces  that  clash,  each  one  seeking  to  dominate  the 

other.     The  most  significant  of  these,  and  the  one  to  which  Plato 

gave  its  classical  formulation,  is  the  one  that  includes  pleasures  as  a 

sequence  of  states  and  happiness,  the  fruit  of  an  enduring  organism. 

Plato's  discussion  of  this  dualism  in  the  Republic  is  the  heart  and 

center  of  Platonic  wisdom. 

10  Pp.  187,  200,  213. 


658  JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY 

A  review  of  these  two  volumes  in  any  adequate  detail  would 
require  a  considerable  essay,  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  so  much  is  left 
out  that  is  contained  in  the  dialogues  themselves,  as  Mr.  More  con- 
fesses with  regret.  A  many-sided  thinker  like  Plato  is  bound  to 
make  different  impressions  on  different  readers.  It  seems  to  the 
present  reviewer  that  Mr.  More  sees  Plato  too  much  with  the  eyes 
of  a  Christian  Platonist,  but  what  he  sees  is  very  interesting  and 
many  things  are  admirably  said,  for  instance  this  about  the  ideas: 
"These  imaginative  projections  of  the  facts  of  the  moral  consciousness 
are  the  true  Platonic  ideas." 

Mr.  More  is  not  a  radical  or  a  "progressive"  where  essentials  are 
concerned,  and  the  great  essential  is  to  control  the  dualism  that  so 
often  disrupts  a  human  character.  His  conviction  is,  he  says,  that 
behind  such  movements  as  the  English  revival  of  philosophic  religion 
in  the  seventeenth  century  and  the  rise  of  romanticism  in  the  eight- 
eenth, "the  strongest  single  influence  has  been  the  perilous  spirit  of 
liberation  brought  into  the  world  by  the  disciple  of  Socrates,  and 
that  our  mental  and  moral  atmosphere,  so  to  speak,  is  still  permeated 
with  inveterate  perversions  of  Plato's  doctrine."  And  this:  "Only 
through  the  centralizing  force  of  religious  faith  or  through  ite  equiva- 
lent in  philosophy  can  the  intellectual  life  regain  its  meaning  and 
authority  for  earnest  men." 

Of  the  two  volumes,  the  earlier  one  is,  I  think,  much  the  more 
interesting.  While  perhaps  nothing  new  is  said,  much  is  very  well 
resaid,  and  it  is  what  can  be  said  many  times  and  in  many  ways.  Mr. 
More  can  make  his  own  translations  into  English  whenever  he  chooses 
to,  and  he  has  given  his  own  translations  at  considerable  length, 
particularly  in  the  volume  on  religion.  The  volume  on  Platonism 
contains  a  study  of  the  Parmenides,  which  ought  to  be  a  help  to  the 
understanding  of  that  perplexing  dialogue. 

Mr.  More  takes  his  Plato  very  literally  indeed.  What  is  put  into 
the  mouth  of  Socrates  must  be  accepted  as  Plato's  opinion  without 
qualification.  Of  Plato  the  artist,  the  poet,  the  dramatist,  capable 
of  humor  and  irony,  there  is  hardly  a  suggestion.  But  then,  the 
work  thus  far  is  really  not  so  much  about  Plato  as  it  is  about  the 
value  of  Platonism  to  a  shell-shocked  world. 

WENDELL  T.  BUSH. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  BRITISH  JOURNAL  OP  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  XIII,  Part  1.  July 
1922.  John  Locke  on  the  General  Influence  of  Studies:  William 
Phillips.  Recent  Contributions  to  the  Theory  of  'Two  Factors.':  C. 
Spearman.  Some  Problems  of  Adolescence :  Ernest  Jones.  A  Vindi- 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  559 

cation  of  the  Resonance  Hypothesis  of  Audition.  IV :  C.  R.  G.  Cosens 
and  H.  Hartridge.  Individual  Differences  in  Listening  to  Music: 
C.  S.  Myers.  Age  Standards  for  the  Separate  Northumberland 
Tests:  O.  H.  Thomson.  The  Biological  and  Social  Significance  of 
the  Expression  of  the  Emotions:  Camille  Nony. 

REVISTA  DI  FiLOSorfA.  Vol.  VIII,  No.  4.  July,  1922.  La  fil- 
osofia  espanola  en  el  ultimo  trienia  (1919-1921) :  Q.  Saldana. 
Economia  del  estado,  social  y  mundial:  A.  Goldschmidt.  Argu- 
mentos  escepticos  y  objeciones  dogmaticas :  L.  Maupas.  El  Derecho 
Social  en  Mejico :  J.  C.  Torres.  La  doctrina  eugenica  y  la  inf ancia 
anormal:  L.  Ciampi. 

REVUE  NEO-SCOLASTIQUE  DE  PHILOSOPHIE.  XXIV,  No.  95.  Au- 
gust, 1922.  L 'Analogic  de  Proportion  chez  Saint  Thomas  d'Aquin: 
B.  Landry.  Les  Elements  de  la  Moralite  des  Actes  chez  Saint 
Thomas  d'Aquin:  D.  Lottin.  Un  nouvel  essai  de  Realisme  en  Amer- 
ique :  R.  Kremer. 

ZEITSCHRIFT  FUR  PSYCHOLOGIE.  Bd.  89,  Heft  4-6.  Zur  Theorie 
der  stroboskopischen  Bewegungen :  F.  Hillebrand.  Die  Erblichkeit 
der  musikalischen  Begabung :  V.  Haeker  und  Th.  Ziehen.  Umrifs- 
skizze  zu  einer  theoretischen  Psychologic :  J.  Lindworsky. 

JOURNAL  DE  PSYCHOLOGIE:  XIX,  No.  7.  July,  1922.  L 'inter- 
pretation du  reve  chez  les  primitif s :  M.  Halbwachs.  Une  expres- 
sion organique  de  la  defense  psychique:  7.  Boas.  Auto-observation 
d'une  hallucination  et  d'une  illusion:  P.  Quercy.  L 'adrenaline  et 
1 'emotion:  A.  Mayer. 

Dasqupta,  Surendranath :  A  History  of  Indian  Philosophy. 
London:  Cambridge  University  Press.  New  York:  Macmillan 
Company.  1922.  Pp.  xvi  +  528. 

Dickinson,  Zenas  Clark:  Economic  Motives.  A  Study  in  the 
Psychological  Foundations  of  Economic  Theory.  Cambridge:  Har- 
vard University  Press.  1922.  Pp.  304.  $2.50. 

Dupreel,  Eugene:  La  Legende  Socratique  et  les  Sources  de 
Platon.  Bruxelles:  Les  Editions  Robert  Sand.  New  York:  Oxford 
University  Press  American  Branch.  1922.  Pp.  448.  $6.00. 

Gemelli,  Fr.  Agostino :  Religione  e  Scienza.  2nd  edition. 
Milano:  Societa  eclitrice  Vita  e  Pensiero.  1922.  369  pp. 

Goldenweisser,  Alexander:  Early  Civilization.  New  York: 
Knopf.  1922.  428  pp. 

Kanovitch,  Abraham:  The  Will  to  Beauty.  New  York:  Gold 
Rose  Printing  Co.  1922.  192  pp. 

Smith,  Henry  Bradford:  Foundations  of  Formal  Logic.  Uni- 
versity of  Pennsylvania  Press.  1922.  56  pp. 

Tassy,  Edme:  La  Philosophie  Constructive.  Paris:  Etienne 
Chiron.  1922.  321  pp. 


'.(.I)  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Stephen,  Karin:  The  Misuse  of  Mind.  Series:  International 
Library  of  Psychology,  Philosophy  and  Scientific  Method.  New 
York :  Harcourt,  Brace  &  Co.  1922.  Pp.  107. 

Thompson,  C.  G. :  The  Ethics  of  William  Wollaston.  Boston : 
Gorham  Press.  1922.  235  pp. 

Coburn,  Charles  A.:  Heredity  of  Wildness  and  Savageness  in 
Mice.  Behavior  Monographs,  Vol.  4,  No.  5.  1922.  Baltimore: 
Williams  and  Wilkins  Co.  71  pp. 

Papini,  Giovanni:  Four  and  Twenty  Minds  (Essays)  Trans- 
lated by  Ernest  Wilkins.  New  York:  Thomas  Y.  Crowell  Co. 
1922.  350pp. 

NOTES  AND  NEWS 

At  the  recent  meeting  of  the  British  Association  at  Hull,  dele- 
gates from  the  University  of  Toronto  extended  a  formal  invitation 
to  the  Association  to  meet  in  Canada  in  1924.  They  promised  an 
enthusiastic  welcome  and  $50,000  toward  defraying  the  expenses 
of  British  scientific  colleagues.  They  requested,  however,  that  the 
date  of  the  Toronto  meeting  should  be  the  second  week  of  Septem- 
ber, that  excursions  to  the  Pacific  should  be  arranged  beforehand, 
and  also  that  any  other  meeting  that  year  at  home  should  be  subse- 
quent and  strictly  subsidiary,  so  that  Toronto  would  have  the  real 
British  Association  meeting  of  1924.  The  offer  was  unanimously 
and  gratefully  accepted. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  21  OCTOBER  12,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


ANEW  conception  that  is  thorough-going  always  simplifies.  In 
fact  it  usually  originates  when  a  prevailing  point  of  view  has 
got  overloaded,  cumbrous  and  involved.  The  notion  of  behavior  is 
already  having  a  simplifying  and  reducing  effect  upon  epistemology 
and  in  my  opinion  is  only  beginning  its  career.  But  a  new  point  of 
view  also  tends  to  oversimplify,  to  neglect,  ignore  and  thereby  in 
effect  to  deny.  It  is  one  thing,  for  example,  to  deny  qualities,  mean- 
ings, feelings,  consciousness,  etc.,  as  they  have  been  defined  by  prior 
theories,  especially  by  modern  psychology  with  its  helplessly  subjec- 
tive and  private  metaphysics.  It  is  another  thing  to  deny  the  facts 
which  common  sense  and  common  speech  independently  of  any 
theory  call  by  these  names.  Personally,  I  believe  that  the  identifi- 
cation of  knowing  and  thinking  with  speech  is  wholly  in  the  right 
direction.  But,  with  one  marked  exception,  I  have  not  seen  any 
analysis  of  speech  which  appears  adequate  or  which  does  not  lay- 
itself  open  to  the  charge  of  omitting  and  virtually  denying  obvious 
facts.1 

1.  When  it  is  asserted  that  speech  as  thought  is  a  reaction,  the 
question  at  once  arises :  What  is  its  stimulus  ?  The  easy  and  simple 
reply  is  wrong.  We  are  likely  to  say  that  speech  is  a  reaction  to  a 
thing  sensibly  present,  that,  for  example,  I  say  "this  is  a  knife"  be- 
cause a  knife  is  sensibly  present  as  a  stimulus  to  speech.  The  be- 
haviorist,  of  all  persons,  can  not  afford  to  give  this  account  of  the 
stimulus  to  speech.  For  if  he  does,  he  subjects  himself  to  a  final 
retort.  The  sensible  presence  of  the  knife  is,  then,  already  a  case  of 
knowledge,  and  speech  instead  of  constituting  knowledge  merely 
voices,  utters  or  reduplicates  a  knowledge  already  there  in  full  ex- 
istence. If  the  stimulus  is  not  a  thing  sensibly  present,  neither  is  it 
merely  some  prior  complete  act  or  piece  of  behavior  which  causes  con- 
tractions in  the  vocal  organs.  The  utterances  of  a  talking-machine 

i  The  exception  is  the  remarkably  clear  and  comprehensive  paper  by  Mead, 
in  this  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIX,  No.  6,  on  "A  Behavioristic  Account  of  the  Signifi- 
cant Symbol. ' ' 

561 


562  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

are  induced  by  an  internal  mechanism  but  they  are  not  speech  or 
knowledge;  neither  is  a  hiccough  or  groan  or  sigh,  although  it  is 
caused  in  the  vocal  musculature  by  prior  organic  conditions. 

There  is  a  difference  between  the  concept  of  stimulus-reaction  and 
that  of  cause-effect.  The  former  includes,  of  course,  the  latter,  but  it 
adds  something.  It  has,  in  addition,  the  property  of  an  adaptation, 
or  maladaptation,  which  is  effected.  But  adaptation  alone  is  not 
enoilgh  to  differentiate  stimulus  and  response  in  the  case  of  speech. 
A  sigh  may  relieve  suffering  and  in  so  far  be  adaptive.  Seeing  as 
an  act  may  be  part  of  the  stimulus  to  saying  "that  is  a  knife,"  but 
it  can  not  be  the  entire  stimulus.  For  seeing  as  a  complete  stimulus 
gives  rise  to  the  response  of  reaching  and  taking  or  withdrawing, 
not  of  speech.  What  has  to  be  accounted  for  is  the  postponement 
of  the  complete  overt  reaction,  and  its  conversion  into  an  intermediate 
vocal  reaction.  There  must  be  some  break  in  the  seeing-reaching 
sequence,  some  obstacle  to  its  occurrence,  to  induce  a  diversion  from 
the  hand  to  the  voice.  There  must  be  a  defective  or  hesitant  connec- 
tion between  seeing  and  handling  which  is  somehow  made  good  and 
whole  by  speech.  Hence  the  stimulus  to  speech  can  not  be  identified, 
per  simpliciter,  with  its  object.  The  latter  is  its  consequence,  not 
its  antecedent. 

2.  Before  fully  developing  the  implications  of  this  point  we 
must  turn  to  another  phase  of  speech  reaction.  Not  every  speech 
reaction,  even  when  genuine  and  not  a  mere  vocalization,  is  a  cogni- 
tive statement  even  by  implication.  Story-telling  need  not  purport 
to  state  "facts"  or  "truths";  its  interest  may  be  increased  by  vrai- 
semblance,  but  this  trait  serves  a  dramatic  or  imaginative  end,  not 
an  intellectual  one.  A  reader  of  Shakespeare  may  become  a  student 
of  the  sources  upon  which  Shakespeare  drew,  and  make  speech  reac- 
tions to  this  study.  Then  the  reaction  is  cognitive.  But  he  need 
not  do  so;  he  may  be  content  to  confine  his  speech  reaction  to  a 
dramatic  production.  Again  the  reader  may  become  interested  in 
whether  Shakespeare  meant  to  represent  Hamlet  as  mad;  then  his 
reaction  is  a  judgment.  But  he  may  be  satisfied  merely  to  use 
speech  as  a  means  of  re-creating  a  Hamlet  either  sane  or  mad ;  as  a 
mode  of  story-telling  or  drama  it  makes  no  difference.  There  is  no 
outside  criterion  till  we  go  outside  of  mere  story-telling.  The 
play's  the  thing  and  it  has  no  object  of  knowledge. 

These  remarks  are  intended  to  call  attention  to  the  need  of  dis- 
covering some  differential  trait  of  those  speech  reactions  which  do 
constitute  knowledge.  A  story  or  play  is  there,  and  the  re-enacting  of 
it  in  a  speech  mode  is  purely  additive.  It  makes  another  piece  of 
behavior,  but  this  new  mode  of  behavior  does  not  react  back  into 


KNOWLEDGE  AND  SPEECH  REACTION  563 

the  play  or  story  or  its  conditions.  It  is  complete  on  its  own  account. 
A  play  of  Shakespeare  may  mean  a  hundred  different  things  to  a 
hundred  different  audiences  or  a  hundred  different  persons  in  the 
same  audience,  and  the  diversity  of  the  hundred  speech  reactions 
evoked  is  no  matter.  The  speech  reactions  need  have  no  connection 
with  what  Shakespeare  himself  meant  in  his  reaction,  beyond  being 
caused  by  the  latter.  But  a  judgment  or  thought  about  what  Shake- 
speare himself  meant  does  not  have  any  such  self-sufficing  independ- 
ence. It  has  to  link  up  with  something  outside  itself.  It  has  to  be  a 
reaction  not  merely  to  the  play  as  a  provocative  cause,  but  has  to  be 
a  response  which  somehow  fits  into  or  answers  to  the  play  as  stimu- 
lus. Our  problem  is  to  name  that  distinctive  feature  of  a  speech 
reaction  which  confers  upon  it  the  quality  of  response,  reply,  an- 
swer; of  supplying  something  lacking  without  it. 

"We  thus  return  to  our  prior  analysis.  The  statement  "this  is  a 
knife"  is  cognitive  because  it  is  more  than  a  mere  evocation  oi  a  prior 
piece  of  behavior.  It  serves  to  supplement  or  complete  a  behavior 
which  is  incomplete  or  broken  without  it.  As  response  it  is  reaction 
in  another  sense  than  when  we  say  in  physics:  action  and  reaction 
are  equal  and  in  opposite  direction.  Some  physical  reactions  are 
quite  independent  of  that  action  to  which  they  are  reactions  except 
in  a  casual  sense.  But  a  response  in  statement  is  intimately  con- 
nected with  that  to  which  it  answers.  It  is  not  merely  to  it  or  away 
from  it,  but  is  back  into  it :  that  is,  it  continues,  develops,  directs 
something  defective  without  it.  Without  speech  reaction  the  action 
which  causes  it  is  blind  trial  or  error ;  with  it,  or  rather  through  it, 
the  evoking  action  becomes  purposive,  that  is,  continuous,  cumulative. 
To  be  more  specific  the  response  "this  is  a  knife"  is  produced  by 
reactions  of  seeing  and  incipient  reactions  of  reaching,  touching, 
handling,  which  are  up  to  the  point  of  speech  reaction  fumbling, 
choked  and  conflicting.  Speech  reaction  unifies  them  into  the  atti- 
tude of  unhesitant  readiness  to  seize  and  cut.  It  integrates  or  co- 
ordinates behavior  tendencies  which  without  it  are  uncertain  and 
more  or  less  antagonistic.  This  trait  is  the  differentia  of  judgment 
from  speech  reaction  in  the  form  of  story  telling  and  vicarious  dra- 
matic reproduction.  Unless  we  acknowledge  and  emphasize  this  trait, 
the  behavioristic  theory  falls  an  easy  victim  to  the  contention  that 
language  merely  echoes  or  puts  into  verbal  form  an  apprehension 
that  is  complete  without  it.  The  dilemma  is  unescapable.  Either 
the  speech  reaction  does  something  to  what  calls  it  out,  modifying  it 
and  giving  it  a  behavior  characteristic  which  it  otherwise  does  not 
have,  or  it  is  mere  utterance  of  what  already  exists  apart  from  it. 

This  fact  throws  light  upon  the  oversimplification  referred  to  at 
the  outset.  It  is  easy  to  overlook  the  modifying,  re-directive  and 


564  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPII  Y 

integrative  function  of  speech  as  a  response.  Then  only  one  side  of 
it  is  recognized,  that  of  its  being  caused  by  a  prior  action.  The 
result  is  an  identification  of  stimulus  and  object  of  knowledge  which 
not  merely  goes  contrary  to  facts  but  which  undermines  the  behavior- 
istic  statement.  For  since  the  stimulus  as  cause  is  there  when  the 
reaction  takes  place,  the  object  must  also  be  there,  if  stimulus  and 
object  are  simply  identified.  Then,  cognitively  speaking,  speech  is 
a  futile  echoing,  however  useful  it  may  be  as  a  practical  device  for 
fixing  attention  or  supplying  a  convenient  memorandum  for  recol- 
lection. 

Mr.  Mursell,  in  his  recent  interesting  article,2  seems  to  me  to 
illustrate  the  oversimplification  in  question  and  also  its  consequences. 
Speaking  of  perceptual  judgments — speech  reactions  which  state 
perceptions — he  says  they  are  "those  Judgments  where  the  stimulus 
of  the  speech  reaction  is  that  to  which  the  judgment  has  reference. 
I  see  a  colored  patch  and  respond  by  saying  'that  is  red.'  I  see 
my  desk  light  burning  and  the  muscles  of  my  vocal  organs  are  in- 
nervated to  make  the  assertion  'the  light  is  burning.'  '  So  far  the 
account  is  inconclusive  with  respect  to  our  problem.  No  one  would 
deny  that  speech  reaction  has  reference  to  its  stimulus  or  that  an 
act  of  seeing  is  at  least  part  of  its  stimulus.  But  the  passage  con- 
tinues as  follows:  "In  such  cases  the  relation  between  the  judg- 
ment and  its  object  seems  sufficiently  clear.  The  object  is  the 
cause  of  the  judgment,  the  causal  nexus  taking  an  intricate  path 
through  the  nervous  ganglia."  (Italics  mine.)  Here  the  nature 
of  the  reference  is  unambiguously  stated.  Stimulus  is  cause,  and 
as  cause  it  is  also  the  object  of  judgment. 

If  the  stimulus  is  not  simply  a  tendency  to  see,  that  is,  an  innerva- 
tion  of  the  optical  apparatus,  but  is  a  seeing  of  "desk-light-burning," 
the  non-behaviorist  can  adequately  retort  that  seeing  the  light  and 
the  desk  and  their  respective  positions  is  already  a  case  of  knowing 
or  judgment,  so  that  speech  is  merely  an  addition,  supernumerary 
for  judgment  though  doubtless  of  practical  and  social  utility.  The 
case  stands  otherwise  if  the  stimulus  is  an  obstructed  or  incomplete 
act  of  vision,  and  speech  serves  to  release,  to  direct  and  clinch  it. 
In  the  latter  case,  the  patch  would  not  be  known  as  red,  say,  or  the 
light  as  the  light  of  a  lamp  on  the  desk  until  the  speech  reaction 
definitely  determined  a  stimulus.  There  is  nothing  paradoxical  in 
this  conception.  We  constantly  react  to  light  by  using  it,  without 
knowing  or  naming  it — without  an  explicit  distinction  and  identifica- 
tion, and  we  very  well  know  in  dealing  with  novelties  how  names 
clear  up  and  fix  otherwise  confusing  and  confused  situations.  Be- 

*  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIX,  p.  187,  "Truth  as  Correspondence." 


KNOWLEDGE  AND  SPEECH  REACTION  565 

havioristically,  above  all,  we  must  conceive  that  speech  response  is 
not  something  final  and  isolated,  but  that  it  operates  in  turn  as  con- 
dition of  some  more  effective  and  adequate  adjustment.  While  prac- 
tically this  function  may  be  often  performed  in  a  direction  away  from 
its  cause,  as  when  we  call  out  to  a  person  in  danger  to  look  out,  with- 
out stopping  to  tell  him  why  he  should  look  out,  intellectually  its  office 
is  turned  toward  the  cause  to  modify  it.  And  the  object  of  judgment 
is  thus  not  the  cause  simply;  it  is  the  consequence,  the  modification 
effected  in  its  cause  by  the  speech  reaction.  The  speech  response 
is  retroactive  as  it  were ;  not  that  it  can  modify  anything  which  has 
passed  out  of  existence,  but  it  influences  a  contemporary  act  of 
vision  and  a  tendency  to  reach  or  handle  so  as  to  give  them  a  di- 
rected unity  which  they  would  not  otherwise  achieve  save  at  the 
termination  of  a  period  of  trial  and  error. 

3.  The  analysis  is  still  oversimplified.  Speaking  is  connected  with 
an  ear  and  auditory  apparatus,  and  their  neuro-muscular  and  intra- 
organic  connections.  It  is  contrary  to  fact  to  identify  a  speech 
reaction  with  simply  the  innervation  of  the  vocal  organs.  This  gives 
no  differentia  of  speech  from  a  sigh,  or  grunt,  or  ejaculation  due  to 
respiratory  reactions  to  pain.  A  speech  reaction  is  the  innerva- 
tion-of-vocal-apparatus-as-stimulus-to-the-responses-of-other-organs- 
through-the-auditory-apparatus.  It  involves  the  auditor  and  his 
characteristic  reaction  to  speech  heard.  Often  and  primarily  the 
auditor  is  another  organism  whose  behavior  is  required  to  complete 
the  speech  reaction,  this  behavior  being  the  objective  aimed  at  in  the 
speech  reaction.3 

When  the  speech  reaction  consists  in  a  "silent"  innervation  the 
principle  is  the  same.  It  is  then  addressed  to  our  own  ear  and  the 
total  connections  thereof.  Instead  of  making  a  command,  or  giving 
warning  or  advice  to  another  agent  for  him  to  react  to,  we  address 
it  to  ourself  as  a  further  re-agent.  The  agent  issuing  the  stimulus 
and  the  one  receiving  it  form  two  agents  or  persons  or  behavior  sys- 
tems. Failure  expressly  to  note  the  implication  of  the  auditor  and 
his  further  behavior  in  a  speech  reaction  is,  I  think,  chiefly  respon- 
sible for  the  common  belief  that  there  is  something  arbitrary,  con- 
ceived in  the  interest  of  upholding  a  behavioristic  theory  at  all  cost,  in 
identifying  thought  with  speech.  For  when  speech  is  confined  to 
mere  vocal  innervations,  the  heart  of  knowledge  is  clearly  not  there. 
But  neither  is  the  heart  of  speech.  Introduce  connection  with  the 
responsive  adjustments  of  the  audience,  and  the  forced  paradox  dis- 
appears. We  have,  as  Mr.  Mead  has  shown,  the  conditions  for 
meaning. 

a  This  is  the  point  which  is  brought  out  so  effectively  in  the  article  by 
Mead  already  referred  to. 


:>MJ  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

A  speech  reaction  is  a  direction  to  subsequent  behavior:  Look 
and  see;  listen  and  hear;  jump,  turn  to  the  left — remarks  ad- 
dressed to  another  who  is  in  connection  with  ourselves,  a  partaker 
in  the  same  behavior  system,  and  then  to  ourselves,  as  a  further 
re-agent,  when  there  is  no  other  person  present. 

Commands,  optatives  and  subjunctives  are  the  primary  modes 
of  speech  reaction;  the  indicative  or  expositive  mood  is  an  ampli- 
fication. For  example,  even  a  treatise  by  a  mathematician  or  chem- 
ist is  a  guide  to  the  undertaking  of  certain  behavior  reactions — a 
series  of  acts  which  when  executed  will  result  in  seeing  the  things 
which  the  author  has  responded  to  with  certain  statements.  It  fol- 
lows that  the  object  of  a  speech  reaction  is  the  concordant  responses 
which  it  sets  up.  Antecedent  stimuli  are  a  part  of  this  object  but 
are  not  the  complete  object  of  knowledge;  the  latter  involves  the 
further  determinations  which  antecedent  stimuli  undergo  by  means 
of  behavior  evoked  by  speech.  The  object  of  knowledge  or  speech 
is  the  ultimate  consent  of  the  coordinated  responses  of  speaker  and 
hearer;  the  object  of  a/firmation  is  the  confirmation  of  co-adapted 
behavior.  Its  object  is  that  future  complex  coordination  of  serial 
acts  into  a  single  behavior-system  which  would  not  exist  without 
it.  One's  responses  are  co-adapted  to  the  auditor's  and  the  audi- 
tor's to  one's  own.  Certain  consequences  follow. 

1.  The  first  is  the  refutation  of  solipsism.  Not  only  can  two 
persons  know  the  same  object,  but  a  single  personal  reaction  can 
not  know  an  identical  object.  As  a  single  and  singular  being  I  may 
make  a  primary  non-cognitive  reaction  to  a  stimulus.  I  may  shiver 
when  the  ear  is  stimulated  in  a  certain  way.  But  when  I  say, 
"that  is  the  noise  of  a  saw"  the  statement  is  addressed  to  the  re- 
sponses of  an  auditor  in  such  a  way  as  to  demand  a  concordant  re- 
action. He  listens  and  looks,  and  says,  "no,  that  is  the  sound  of 
an  axle  of  a  wheel. ' '  Then  I  have  to  look,  to  respond  with  further 
behavior.  The  speech  reaction  is  not  complete  till  a  concordant  re- 
sponse is  established.  In  other  words,  speech  is  conversation ;  it  in- 
volves a  duality  of  experiences  or  views.  A  single  presence  or  view 
does  not  constitute  judgment  or  statement.  This  particular 
manner  of  putting  the  fact  may  be  unusual  but  there  is  nothing 
strikingly  novel  in  the  conception.  Cognition  involves  recognition, 
acknowledgment,  a  contrast  and  connection  of  two  different  times 
or  places  of  experience  by  means  of  which  a  distinctive  identifica- 
tion is  set  up.  A  single  act  can  not,  as  singular,  establish  the  identi- 
fication required  to  characterize  an  event  as  an  object.  There  must 
be  recurrence  in  a  slightly  different  context.  This  is  a  thing  that 
requires  a  response  like  that  made  before,  or  which  will  exact  a 


KNOWLEDGE  AND  SPEECH  REACTION  567 

like  response  in  the  future,  or  of  some  other  re-agent  in  the  present. 
And  without  the  sameness  or  correspondence  of  the  responses  of 
the  two  times  or  places,  there  is  literally,  contra-diction.  An  ob- 
ject of  knowledge  must  consistently  cover  or  comprehend  responses 
to  at  least  two  distinct  stimuli. 

2.  This  conclusion  has  a  direct  bearing  upon  the  nature  of  the 
correspondence  which  defines  truth.  The  correspondence  is  found 
in  the  inclusion  in  a  single  contemporary  behavior  system  of  di- 
verse behavior  reactions.  No  correspondence  can  be  conclusively 
established  between  a  present  response  and  a  past  one  in  their 
separation,  or  between  a  present  one  and  a  future  one  in  their 
separateness.  There  must  be  one  harmonious  behavior  function 
which  includes  the  elements  of  both.  Mr.  Mursell  in  the  article 
referred  to  makes  correspondence  retroactive.  He  says:4  "When  I 
assert  that  Caesar  crossed  the  Rubicon,  I  am  reproducing  the 
original  reaction  made  by  observers  two  thousand  years  ago,  who 
saw  him  splash  through  the  stream  and  found  in  the  sight  a  stimu- 
lus to  the  response  'He  has  crossed  the  Rubicon.'  '  This  account 
involves  the  mistake  pointed  out  in  the  case  of  the  statement  "this 
is  red  color."  It  assumes  that  the  object  is  known  and  also  truly 
known  prior  to  the  speech  reaction.  How  do  I  know  that  some 
former  observer  made  the  speech  reaction  ascribed  to  him?  This 
ascription  is  the  point  at  issue,  and  the  account  quoted  merely  begs 
the  question.  A  correct  statement  of  the  data  that  Mr.  Mursell 
recognizes  would  be:  "I  say  that  an  observer  two  thousand  years 
ago  said  that  Caesar  has  crossed  the  Rubicon;  then  I  reproduce 
that  saying  on  my  own  account.  Then  I  say  that  the  two  sayings 
agree  or  correspond."  Undoubtedly  they  do.  But  at  no  point 
have  I  got  beyond  my  own  sayings.  The  correspondence  is  merely 
between  a  saying  of  my  own  about  what  some  one  else  said  with 
another  saying  of  my  own.  There  is  only  a  new  kind  of  solipsism, 
that  of  private  speech.  In  this  historical  case,  I  clearly  can  not 
direct  my  remark  to  a  man  long  since  dead  and  secure  concordant 
behavior  response  from  him.  But  I  do  address  myself  to  others 
and  say  that  if  they  will  look  at  historic  records,  including  those 
of  a  subsequent  course  of  events,  their  responses  will  correspond  to 
mine — or  that  the  different  reactions  will  all  enter  into  a  single  com- 
plex behavior  system. 

Another  illustration  of  Mr.  Mursell 's  brings  out  the  same  points. 
He  says:  "Suppose  I  say  Napoleon's  tomb  is  in  Paris.  Let  us  as- 
sume that  I  read  the  words  somewhere.  Pushing  back  along  the 
chain  of  recorded  responses  of  which  the  printed  symbols  that  I 
*  P.  187. 


568  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

saw  are  the  last,  I  come  finally  to  the  place  where  the  original  ob- 
server, who  started  tne  whole  series,  stood.  I  am  directed  to  a 
particular  locus,  and  there  I  receive  a  stimulus  that  issues  in  the 
response,  'Yes,  Napoleon's  tomb  is  in  Paris.'  And  this  it  is  which 
constitutes  the  truth  of  the  judgment.  .  .  .  The  chain  of  recorded 
responses  always  directs  us  to  some  specific  locus."8  The  last 
statement  must  be  unqualifiedly  admitted.  But  what  and  where 
is  the  locus  ?  If  it  is  merely  past — and  not  a  stimulus- response  con- 
tinuing into  the  present — then  I  can  only  state  that  "I  say  that  an 
original  observer  said  that  the  tomb  is  in  Paris."  In  short,  as  I 
push  back  along  the  chain,  I  finally  come  after  all  only  to  my  own 
saying  about  what  another  said.  If  I  go  to  Paris  then  indeed  I 
come  upon  quite  another  saying  which  is  congruous  with  my  prior 
saying  that  the  tomb  is  in  Paris,  but  in  this  case  the  object  is  not 
one  of  a  retroactive  response.  Or,  I  may  respond  without  going 
to  Paris  in  such  a  way  as  to  call  out  reactions  from  other  persons 
who  make  the  same  deliverance — that  the  tomb  is  in  Paris.  Here 
also  the  object  is  the  attained  co-adaptations  in  behavior. 

Supposing  we  take  a  judgment  about  an  event  in  the  geological 
ages  preceding  the  existence  of  human  beings  or  any  organisms 
possessed  of  speech  reactions.  In  such  instances,  it  is  clear  that 
there  can  be  no  question  of  correspondence  with  the  speech  reac- 
tion of  a  contemporary  observer.  By  description  the  retroactive 
correspondence  of  sayings  is  ruled  out.  Yet  no  one  doubts  that 
there  are  some  judgments  about  this  ancient  state  of  affairs  which 
are  truer  than  others.  How  can  this  be  possible,  since  there  can  be 
no  question  of  reproducing  the  judgment  of  an  observer!  If  we 
say  that  what  we  now  judge  is  what  a  contemporary  observer  would 
have  said  if  he  had  been  present,  we  are  clearly  begging  the  ques- 
tion. Nor  could  a  contemporary  observer  have  made  as  accurate 
and  comprehensive  a  judgment  in  some  respects  as  we  can  make, 
since  we  can  also  judge  what  occurred  at  a  given  period  in  the 
light  of  what  happened  afterwards.  Clearly  our  speech  reaction 
is  to  observations  of  present  perceptions  of  data,  rocks,  fossils,  etc. 
The  other  auditor  and  speaker  to  whom  the  statements  are  ad- 
dressed are  other  possible  observers  of  these  and  similar  data.  The 
ulterior  "object"  is  the  concordant,  mutually  reinforcing  behavior 
system,  including,  of  course,  the  speech  responses.  Sciousness  in 
this,  as  in  other  cases,  is  con-sciousness.  And  this  equating  is  not 
a  mere  figure  of  speech ;  it  gives  the  original  meaning  of  the  word. 

Summing  up,  we  may  say  that  there  are  three  types  of  response 
which  it  is  necessary  to  distinguish.  First,  there  is  direct  or- 
gan ic  response-of -th e-autonom ic-and-sensori-central-mot or-sy stems-to 

•  Op.  ci*.,  p.  188. 


KNOWLEDGE  AND  SPEECH  REACTION  569 

stimuli.  These  stimuli  are  not,  for  and  in  the  reaction,  objects. 
Their  connection  with  response  is  causal  rather  than  cognitional. 
The  reaction  is  physico-chemical,  though  it  may  terminate  in  a 
spatial  or  molar  change.  Neither  the  stimulus  nor  the  response  is 
an  object  of  knowledge,  though  it  may  become  part  of  an  object- 
to-be-known.  If  the  stimulus  were  adequate  or  complete,  complete 
adaptative  response  or  use  would  take  place.  Being  incomplete, 
it  is  a  challenge  to  a  further  response  which  will  give  it  determinate 
character.  Thereby  the  to-be-known  becomes  an  object  of  knowl- 
edge; it  becomes  an  answer  instead  of  a  query. 

Secondly,  the  speech  response  occupies  an  intermediate  position. 
By  clinching,  fixing  its  stimulus,  it  releases  further  modes  of  re- 
sponse. Saying  that  the  colored  patch  is  red  enables  us  to  take  it 
as  the  thing  we  have  been  hunting  for,  or  to  react  to  it  as  a  definite 
warning  of  danger.  The  prior  activities  form  part  of  the  subject- 
matter  of  the  thing  thus  known.  But  they  are  not  the  object 
known.  The  object  known  is  the  coordination  of  the  prior  behavior 
with  the  consequent  behavior  which  is  effected  by  the  medium  of 
speech.  Till  the  assumption  is  banished  that  stimulus  to  knowing 
and  object  of  knowledge  are  the  same  thing,  the  analysis  of  knowl- 
edge and  truth  will  be  confused.  Thirdly,  the  eventual  coordina- 
tion of  behavior  involves  the  response  of  a  further  re-agent,  namely, 
the  auditor,  whether  another  organism  or  one 's  own.  This  coordina- 
tion of  the  activity  of  speaker  and  hearer  forms  the  ulterior  object 
of  knowledge.  As  a  co-ordination  or  co-adaptation  of  at  least  two 
respondents,  it  constitutes  that  correspondence  which  we  call 
knowledge  or  truth.  Correspondence  of  past  and  present  responses 
can  be  determined  only  by  means  of  a  further  response  which  in- 
cludes both  of  them  within  itself  in  a  unified  way.  The  theory  ex- 
plains the  relation  of  truth  to  consistency  as  well  as  to  correspond- 
ence. The  different  responses  must  consist,  cohere,  together.  Con- 
sistency gets  an  objective,  non-mentalistic  meaning  when  it  is  under- 
stood to  mean  capacity  for  integration  of  different  responses  in  a 
single  more  comprehensive  behavior. 

We  may  conclude  by  suggesting  a  possible  explanation  of  the 
oversimplification  of  the  behavioristic  account  of  speech  which  has 
been  pointed  out.  Introspective  psychology  of  necessity  broke  up 
the  subject-matter  of  psychology  into  a  number  of  disjecta  membra, 
of  disjoined  fragments  treated  as  independent  self-sufficing  wholes. 
I  say  "of  necessity"  because  the  connecting  links  of  these  frag- 
ments are  found  in  a  context  of  environmental  conditions  and  or- 
ganic behavior  of  which  the  introspectionist  can  not  be  aware. 
Now  behaviorism  has  too  often  confined  itself  to  finding  behavior- 


570  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

istic  counterparts  of  the  same  material  and  topics  with  which  intro- 
spective psychology  has  dealt."  Consequently  actual  and  concrete 
behavior  has  been  broken  up  into  a  number  of  disjoined  pieces 
instead  of  being  analyzed  freely  on  its  own  account.  Thus  certain 
errors  of  introspective  psychology  have  been  reduplicated  in  the 
very  behavioristic  psychology  which  is  a  protest  against  introspec- 
tionism. 

JOHN  DEWET. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVIBSITT. 


present  age  may  not  unfairly  be  characterized  as  one  inl<-ni 
J-  upon  immediate  results.  The  remarkable  achievements  of  the 
sciences,  pure  and  applied,  seemingly  put  the  philosopher,  the  plod- 
ding student  of  ultimate  principles,  to  shame,  unless  he,  too,  can 
produce  for  the  edification  of  an  insatiable  public  some  new  and 
novel  contributions  pointing  directly  to  the  advancement  of  the  in- 
dividual and  social  good.  While  psychologists  are  busy  devising 
intelligence  tests,  or  performing  hypothetical  experiments  upon  the 
human  being,  under  the  inspiration  of  "behaviorism,"  quite  as  if 
man  were  a  lower  species  of  animal,  the  philosopher  must  evidently 
do  something  to  "save  caste,"  at  least  by  way  of  showing  his  inter- 
est in  such  scientific  advances. 

To  the  attempt  to  keep  in  touch  with  these  latest  developments 
and  to  express  his  views  on  the  various  ethical  and  sociological 
problems  associated  with  them,  Professor  Ralph  Barton  Perry  is 
devoting  his  best  attention;  it  is,  therefore,  by  the  study  of  his 
writings  that  one  may  hope  most  conveniently  to  gain  an  under- 
standing of  the  philosophical  implications  involved  in  these  move- 
ments. It  is  possible,  however,  that  in  his  preoccupation  with  the 
treatment  of  specific  details,  the  reader  may  sometimes  lose  sight  of 
the  fundamental  principles  upon  which  Professor  Perry's  particular 
solution  of  these  problems  depends.  Such  being  the  case,  it  seems 
essential  to  pass  in  review  Professor  Perry's  various  utterances 
with  the  special  purpose  of  bringing:  these  principles  and  presup- 
positions to  light ;  to  see  in  general  how  he  conceives  of  the  relation 

«  The  case  is  quite  analogous  with  the  situation  described  by  Mr.  Kantor 
with  reference  to  the  nervous  system.  See  his  article  in  this  JOURNAL,  Vol. 
XIX,  p.  38,  on  "The  Nervous  System,  Psychological  Fact  or  Fiction?"  As 
Mr.  Kantor  states,  too  often  "the  nervous  system  ia  taken  to  be  the  tangible 
counterpart  of  the  intangible  psychic."  Similarly,  certain  modes  of  behaviors 
have  been  treated  as  objective  substitutes  for  prior  subjective  entities  and 
processes. 


PROFESSOR  PERRY'S  EMPIRICISM  571 

between   science  and  philosophy;   and   in  particular  what   is  his 
theory  of  the  nature  and  functions  of  the  mind. 

In  his  Presidential  address  before  the  American  Philosophical 
Association,  December,  1920,1  Professor  Perry  presents  a  brief 
summary  of  many  of  the  views  expressed  in  his  previous  articles, 
so  we  may  conveniently  use  that  paper  as  the  starting  point  of  the 
present  discussion,  supplementing  it,  when  necessary,  by  reference 
to  his  other  writings. 

Professor  Perry  declares  in  this  address  that  "...  the  great 
philosophical  enterprise  of  the  immediate  future  is  the  naturalistic 
study  of  man  as  a  part  of  nature,  interchangeable  and  interactive 
with  his  environment. " 2  To  accomplish  this  purpose  entails,  to  his 
mind,  what  some  of  his  readers  may  consider  a  particularly  novel 
conception  of  the  relation  between  philosophy  and  the  natural  sci- 
ences, including  within  that  division  psychology.  "The  leaders  of 
contemporary  thought,  such  as  James,  Bergson,  Dewey,  and  Russell, 
are  distinguished  by  the  utter  lawlessness  with  which  they  intro- 
duce philosophy  into  their  psychology  and  psychology  into  their 
philosophy.  Perhaps  they  do  not  know  the  difference;  in  any  case 
they  ignore  it.  ...  Scorning  schematic  barriers  and  scientific  eti- 
quette they  bluntly  assume  that  the  facts  about  human  nature  are  all 
to  be  found  in  one  place,  and  that  it  is  not ^  significant  by  what  door 
you  enter. ' ' 3 

In  other  words,  both  philosophers  and  psychologists  are  in 
search  of  the  same  facts,  and,  forsaking  dialectics,  are  to  "observe 
what  actually  transpires."4  Not  "idle  speculation,"  but  "direct 
observation "  is  to  be  the  source  of  all  our  knowledge,  both  scientific 
and  philosophical.  And,  to  make  more  explicit  his  point  of  view, 
Professor  Perry  remarks  that  "...  a  careful  effort  to  describe  the 
act  by  which  a  knower  selects  his  object,  or  the  act  of  meaning,  or 
the  act  of  sense-perception,  will  inevitably  lead  an  empiricist,  .  . 
to  attach  central  importance  to  the  functioning  of  the  physical  or- 
ganism. ' ' 5 

What,  first  of  all,  is  said  in  general  of  such  a  notion  of  the  rela- 
tion between  philosophy  and  science?  Professor  Perry  has  stated 
his  case  with  such  cheerful  and  dogmatic  assurance  that  the  reader 
is  justified  in  demanding  conclusive  evidence  in  its  favor.  Cer- 
tainly it  is  not  supported  by  a  historical  study  of  the  course  of  hu- 
man thought ;  never  in  the  past  have  philosophy,  and  either  science 

i"The  Appeal  to  Keason,"  Phil.  Rev.,  XXX,  2,  pp.  131-169. 

2  Phil.  Rev.,  XXX,  2,  p.  136. 

«J6id.,  p.  137. 

*  Present  Philosophical  Tendencies,  pp.  322-3. 

s  Phil.  Rev.,  XXX,  4,  p.  407  (italics  mine). 


572  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOI'JI  Y 

in  general,  or  philosophy  and  any  particular  science,  for  long  em- 
ployed the  same  methods  or  oc<Mipi«'<l  themselves  with  identical 
problems.  In  the  very  nature  of  the  case,  and  for  the  sake  of  clar- 
ity in  defining  issues,  it  would  seem  that  certain  fundamental  dis- 
stinctions  between  philosophy  and  science  must  be  maintained.  So 
long  as  science  must  resort  to  abstraction  in  order  to  attain  its 
legitimate  ends,  just  so  long  must  philosophy  point  out  and  even 
insist  upon  the  necessity  of  a  reinterpretation  of  scientific  conclu- 
sions in  the  light  of  the  more  ultimate  principles,  immanent  in  ex- 
perience as  a  whole  rather  than  in  any  one  part  of  it,  which  it  is 
the  proper  business  of  the  philosopher  to  bring  to  expression. 
Surely  it  is  to  the  advantage  both  of  the  scientist  and  of  the  phi- 
losopher to  recognize  such  a  distinction  as  this,  and  it  would  not  be 
difficult  to  suggest  other  important  differences,  e.g.,  those  concerned 
with  the  problem  of  values. 

Then  again  it  is  a  question  whether  or  not  the  "leaders  of  con- 
temporary thought"  whom  Professor  Perry  mentions  as  his  sole 
authority  in  support  of  his  contention  of  the  present-day  intercon- 
nection between  psychology  and  philosophy,  would  themselves  ac- 
cept his  statement  on  their  behalf.  Bergson,  for  example,  insists 
that  science  fails  to  grasp  the  concrete  nature  of  things  simply  be- 
cause it  is  doomed  to  proceed  by  means  of  the  abstract  categories 
supplied  by  the  intellect ;  to  get  at  reality  the  philosopher  must  em- 
ploy another  faculty,  more  suited  to  its  task,  namely  the  intuition. 
There  could  hardly  be  a  sharper  distinction,  at  least  in  method- 
ology, between  the  two  fields.  And  of  course  there  are  other  con- 
temporaries, whose  views  are  quite  as  worthy  of  respect  as  are  those 
of  the  authorities  he  cites,  who  would  very  definitely  reject  Profes- 
sor Perry's  viewpoint. 

Nevertheless,  the  adoption  of  any  other  point  of  view  than  that 
represented  by  his  fellow  empiricists,  is  contemptuously  cast  aside 
as  due  to  "sentimental"  or  "religious"  prejudices.*  Such  "pure 
speculation,"  it  is  urged,  may  be  a  harmless  enough  pursuit,  like 
a  day-dream,  but  it  is  as  little  in  touch  with  actual  experience  and 
the  "facts"  of  human  existence.  That  is  to  say,  Professor  Perry 
deliberately  refuses  to  recognize  as  facts  worthy  of  serious  philosoph- 
ical consideration,  any  particular  facts  other  than  those  involved 
in  the  functioning  of  the  physical  organism.  To  be  a  fact  means, 
then,  it  would  seem,  to  be  expressible  in  biological  categories. 

With  the  material  adequacy  of  this  conception  we  shall  deal  in 
the  later  part  of  the  discussion.  Our  immediate  concern  is  with 
the  nature  of  the  "scientific"  method  which  is  held  to  be  so  all-im- 

•  Cf .  The  Pretent  Conflict  of  Ideal*,  pp.  378-9  and  pastim. 


PROFESSOR  PERRY'S  EMPIRICISM  573 

portant.  It  seemingly  is  implied  in  the  passages  quoted  above  that 
by  mere  observation  we  may  hope  to  discover  the  facts  about  hu- 
man life  and  experience,  and  then,  presumably,  will  go  on  to  formu- 
late the  significant  laws  of  human  nature  on  the  basis  of  these 
previously  discovered  facts.  But  quite  irrespective  of  the  identity 
or  non-identity  of  philosophical  and  scientific  methodology,  sci- 
ence, simply  qua  science,  does  not,  and  logically  can  not,  follow 
such  a  procedure.  Scientific  experience  flatly  contradicts  the  as- 
sertion that  there  are  bare  original  particulars,  existing  by  them- 
selves, as,  e.g.,  the  doctrine  of  external  relations  would  seem  to  im- 
ply, upon  which  the  scientist  proceeds  to  direct  his  observation, 
for  the  purpose  of  later  framing  laws  and  hypotheses  about  them. 
For  the  scientist  a  fact  is  a  fact — can  only  be  a  fact — in  so  far  as 
it  is  already  associated,  or  capable  of  association,  in  his  experience, 
with  other  facts,  forming  a  more  or  less  consistent  system.  In  other 
words,  to  possess  any  scientific  significance,  to  exist  at  all  for  the 
scientist,  or  for  that  matter,  for  anybody,  particular  facts  and  gen- 
eral laws  logically  imply  each  other,  and  are  inseparable  aspects  of 
a  systematic  dialectic. 

It  seems,  therefore,  that  not  only  is  Professor  Perry's  concep- 
tion of  the  relation  of  science  to  philosophy  open  to  criticism  on  the 
basis  of  the  nature  of  the  problems  with  which  they  are  respectively 
concerned,  but  that  so  long  as  the  methods  of  science  itself  are  in 
dispute,  no  correct  solution  of  the  larger  problem  can  be  hoped  for. 
Let  us,  however,  except  for  these  cursory  remarks,  waive  for  the 
moment  both  the  very  dubious  conception  of  philosophy  as  sharing 
the  same  problems  with  psychology  or  any  other  sciences,  and  the 
complementary  assertion  of  identity  of  method  in  the  two  cases. 
Let  us  rather  turn  to  an  examination  of  the  particular  facts  which 
Professor  Perry  has  discovered,  by  observing  "what  actually  trans- 
pires ' '  about  human  consciousness  and  some  of  its  typical  products. 
For  after  all,  "the  proof  of  the  pudding  is  in  the  eating,"  and  in 
a  certain  sense  the  proof  of  any  method  in  philosophy  lies  in  the 
results  which  it  achieves ;  in  the  degree  to  which  it  serves  adequately 
to  explain  our  actual  experience.  We  shall  see  that  not  only  do 
these  facts  fail  to  represent  the  real  nature  of  man's  mind,  but — 
what  is,  if  possible,  even  more  serious  from  Professor  Perry 's  stand- 
point— that  they  even  prove  adequate  to  the  task  of  defining  con- 
sciousness in  agreement  with  his  own  philosophical  principles,  and 
therefore,  require  considerable  supplementation  from  the  abhorred 
field  of  "pure  speculation." 

First  as  to  consciousness.  In  Present  Philosophical  Tendencies7 
it  is  defined,  in  accordance  with  the  principle  of  attaching  "central 

7  Pp.  322ff. 


.,71  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

importance  to  the  functioning  of  the  physical  organism/'  as  "a 
species  of  function  exercised  by  an  organism."  It  is  "a  selective 
response  to  a  pre-existing  and  independently  existing  environment." 
Now,  however  adequate  such  a  definition  may  be  for  the  immedi- 
ate purposes  of  psychology — and  perhaps  we  may  leave  it  to  the 
scientific  psychologist  to  decide  the  question  for  himself — the  phi- 
losopher, it  would  seem,  is  in  duty  bound  to  point  out  the  obvious 
abstraction  contained  in  it.  For  of  what  "fact"  can  a  serious  em- 
piricist be  more  certain  than  that  an  "independently  existing  en- 
vironment" is  not  a  part  of  his  actual  experience?  At  every  in- 
stant, to  examine  the  matter  no  further,  man  is  transforming  this 
supposedly  independent  environment;  indeed  his  very  presence  in 
the  world  is  already  an  implicit  transformation  in  the  shape  of  added 
values  and  deeper  meanings.  Thus  a  more  flagrant  case  of  "pure 
speculation"  it  would  be  difficult  to  mention.  There  is  no  element 
in  concrete  experience  that  it  serves  to  explain ;  it  stands  there  on 
its  own  merits  as  an  unwarranted  assumption  which  the  philosopher 
would  do  well  to  avoid  until  all  other  more  concrete  possibilities  had 
been  exhausted. 

But  Professor  Perry  does  not  rest  here;  he  proceeds  to  locate 
consciousness  existentially  in  space  and  time.  We  find  (would  Pro- 
fessor Perry  say  "observe?")  that  it  is  "only  one  kind  of  thing 
among  many  " ; 8  it  intervenes  as  an  arc  in  the  causal  circuit  of  the 
nervous  system,  comprised  of  stimulus  at  one  end  and  response  at 
the  other.9  But  here  is  where  observers  apparently  disagree,  since 
the  thoroughgoing  behaviorist,  the  essence  of  whose  method  is  ob- 
servation, denies  the  existence  of  any  such  factor  as  consciousness. 
Parenthetically,  we  may  remark  that  such  confusion  is  due  in  part 
to  an  uncritical  use  of  the  terms  "stimulus"  and  "response"; 
terms  which  some  physiologists  are  learning  to-  treat  with  more 
circumspection  and  care  than  formerly.10 

However  that  may  be,  the  further  question  naturally  arises  as 
to  why  it  is  necessary  to  conceive  of  consciousness,  for  scientific 
purposes,  in  existential  terms  at  all.  Many  psychologists,  except 
perhaps  those  who  reject  the  concept  altogether,  would  rest  con- 
tent with  defining  it,  as  indeed  Professor  Perry  himself  does  at  the 
outset,  as  a  process,  an  activity,  exercised  by  the  natural  organism. 
And,  moreover,  this  is  all  that  consistency  with  Professor  Perry's 
psychological  principles  demands.  Then  why  attempt  to  ascribe  to 

•  Present  Philotophical  Tendencies,  pp.  322-3. 

•Of.  "A  Behavioriatic  View  of  Purpose,"  this  JOURNAL,  XVTII,  4,  pp. 
86-105. 

"McDougall,  "Prolegomena  to  Psychology"  in  the  Psychological  Review, 
XXIX,  1,  pp.  1-43. 


PROFESSOR  PERRY'S  EMPIRICISM  575 

it  characteristics  usually  associated  with  physical  thinghood?  The 
answer  is,  as  indicated  above,  that  the  merely  scientific  account 
proves  inadequate  for  philosophical  purposes  and  hence  must  be 
supplemented  by  certain  hypothetical  principles  of  nee-realism. 
Thus  the  account  of  the  neo-realistic  solution  of  the  riddle  of  the 
dualism  of  mind  and  body  runs  as  follows :  ' '  Consciousness  is  homo- 
geneous with  the  rest  of  the  world  in  the  sense  that  it  is  composed 
ultimately  of  the  same  elements"11 — or  "neutral  entities."  That 
is,  consciousness,  a  tree,  man,  a  mathematical  system, — in  short, 
whatever  in  any  sense  exists,  or  may  be  thought  about — reduces  by 
realistic  analysis  to  these  same  neutral  entities.  But  a  neutral 
entity,  whatever  else  it  may  be,  is  not  an  empirical  fact;  it  pos- 
sesses no  properties  amenable  to  scientific  or  to  logical  scrutiny ;  it 
has  nothing  to  do  with  the  functioning  of  the  physical  organism, 
empirically  considered;  it  is  simply  a  metaphysically  postulated 
element  conceived,  principally,  it  would  seem,  for  the  purpose  of 
constructing  reality  out  of  bits. 

Such  is  the  stratagem  to  which  Professor  Perry's  neo-realistic 
empiricism  is  forced  by  a  natural  logic  more  powerful  than  any 
resolution-  an  individual  thinker  or  group  of  thinkers  may  form 
not  to  recognize  it.  However  much  he  may  insist  upon  construing 
reality  "scientifically"  in  terms  of  particular  observed  facts  only 
externally  related  to  one  another,  however  much  he  may  resolve  to 
focus  attention  solely  upon  the  particular  physical  organism,  the 
neo-realist  is  at  last  driven  to  posit  some  sort  of  a  logical  connec- 
tion, an  artificial  universal,  to  take  the  place  of  the  real  universal 
binding  these  particulars  together.  Having  forsaken  the  real  uni- 
versals  displaying  the  identity  in  diversity  actually  found  in  ex- 
perience, he  is  obliged  to  adopt  as  a  substitute  some  logical  fiction 
such  as  the  neutral  entities,  thereby  reducing  the  articulated  uni- 
verse to  a  bare  and  formal  identity  wholly  unlike  that  known  to 
concrete  experience.  In  other  words,  we  are  contemplating  the  logi- 
cal results  of  artificially  separating  factors,  such  as  the  individual 
and  the  external  environment,  which  actually  are  intimately  bound 
together  in  the  concrete  whole  of  things.  It  is  the  attempt  to  em- 
ploy in  philosophy  the  method  so  successful  and  legitimate  in  sci- 
ence— the  tool  of  abstraction.  So  that  how  Professor  Perry  is  to 
reconcile  his  insistence  upon  the  employment  of  solely  empirical 
"scientific"  methods  of  direct  observation  in  the  acquisition  of  the 
"facts"  of  experience  with  the  purely  speculative  theory  which  he 
as  a  philosopher  sees  fit  to  adopt,  we  must  leave  to  him  to  explain. 
One  thing  is  evident,  namely,  that  not  the  facts  alone  or  even 

11  The  Present  Conflict  of  Ideals,  p.  376. 


576  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

principally,  but  certain  assumptions,  furnish  the  real  basis  of  his 
conception  of  the  nature  of  consciousness.  Yet  it  is  not  against  the 
making  of  assumptions  that  one  may  complain,  for  all  thinking  in- 
volves such  a  factor, — though,  incidentally,  Professor  Perry's  own 
principles  seem  logically  to  preclude  for  him  the  making  of  them — 
but  rather  the  uncritical,  dogmatic  assertion  of  these  particular 
ones,  as  if  they  required  no  examination  as  to  adequacy  but  were 
self-evident  and  directly  derived  from  the  facts  of  experience. 

Thus  the  net  result  of  the  application  of  Professor  Perry's  em- 
piricism to  the  facts  of  consciousness  is  failure  to  derive  a  consis- 
tent or  satisfactory  account  of  its  nature.  The  great  wonder,  how- 
ever, is,  not  that  the  outcome  of  such  a  self-contradictory  procedure 
should  have  resulted  in  failure,  but  rather  that  it  could  ever  have 
been  thought  to  possess  any  possible  value  as  a  method  of  philosoph- 
ical explanation.  It  should  serve  as  a  concrete  example  of  the 
results  to  be  expected  from  the  attempt  to  disregard  the  logical 
principle  that  form  and  matter  mutually  condition  each  other;  that 
there  is  no  general  abstract  logical  constant  or  bare  identity  such 
as  a  neutral  entity,  which  can  be  applied  effectively  and  indiscrimi- 
nately as  a  principle  of  explanation  to  each  and  every  part  of 
experience  on  the  general  assumption  that  all  experience  is  reduci- 
ble to  the  existential  or  quasi-existential  terms  of  natural  science. 

Indeed,  a  close  inspection  of  Professor  Perry's  various  writings 
only  goes  to  confirm  the  first  impression  that  we  have  to  do  with 
a  serenely  nai've  point  of  view  with  regard  to,  for  example,  such 
problems  as  that  of  the  nature  of  the  mind,  quite  on  a  level  with  that 
of  the  ordinary  uncritical  writer  of  text-books  on  physiological  psy- 
chology. He  makes  no  attempt  to  examine  the  presuppositions  in- 
volved in  such  an  attitude,  and  the  outcome,  thus  far  at  least,  of  the 
identification  of  science  and  philosophy,  as  proposed  by  Professor 
Perry,  is,  therefore,  a  mere  juxtaposition  of  certain  philosophical 
principles,  not  cogent  to  the  problems  at  hand,  with  the  uncriticized 
results  obtained  from  a  narrow  field  of  scientific  investigation. 

And  when  we  turn  from  a  consideration  of  his  conception  of 
the  nature  of  consciousness  itself  to  his  application  of  the  concep- 
tion to  an  interpretation  of  such  mental  products  and  activities  as 
•  purposiveness  and  belief,  we  shall  see  that  here,  even  more  ex- 
plicitly, the  attempt  to  unite  philosophy  and  science  in  a  single, 
identical  enterprise,  results  in  a  merely  scientific  outlook,  with  all 
of  its  attendant  abstractions  and  na'ivetS. 

"Biologists,"  Professor  Perry  declares,  "and  even  chemists  are 
discussing  teleology  with  open  and  receptive  minds."12  This  re- 

»  Phil.  Bev.,  XXX,  2,  p.  136. 


PROFESSOR  PERRY'S  EMPIRICISM  577 

mark  is  important  because  our  writer  says  elsewhere:  "Man  and 
his  faculties  belong  to  the  fields  of  the  biological  sciences  and  are 
therefore  subject  to  the  methods  and  laws  which  are  proper  in  that 
field. ' ' 13  Evidently  we  may  expect  that  human  purposiveness  as 
|  well  as  consciousness  will  be  defined  in  accordance  with  the  biologi- 
cal categories.  We  may  conceive  of  the  human  mind,  Professor 
Perry  explains,  as  a  "unified  reaction-system  which  .  .  .  will  con- 
trol both  the  internal  adjustments  of  the  organism  and  its  dealings 
with  the  external  environment."  If  the  response  be  impeded  by  an 
obstacle  a  series  of  trials  and  errors  ensue  until  a  reaction  occurs 
"by  which  the  impediment  is  removed."14  "The  object  exciting 
the  successful  response  will  thereafter  be  charged  with  a  meaning 
or  will  partially  reawaken  that  same  response.  .  .  .  When  a  re- 
sponse occurs  on  that  account,  that  is,  when  an  act  is  performed  be- 
cause in  its  implicit  form  it  coincides  with  the  unfulfilled  phase  of 
a  determining  tendency,  we  may  say  that  it  is  performed  purpo- 
sively. ' ' 15  Note,  moreover,  that  ' '  a  belief  of  some  sort,  an  act  of 
the  intellect  which  is  either  true  or  erroneous,  is  ...  invariably 
one  of  the  factors  in  a  complete  human  act.  .  .  .  These  two  factors 
[belief  and  determining  tendency]  unite  to  constitute  purposive 
action.  .  .  . " 16  That  is  to  say,  we  use  our  intellect  as  a  comple- 
ment to  our  other  faculties  to  perform  ideal  experiments  to  de- 
termine how  particular  ends  may  successfully  be  attained.  In  Pro- 
fessor Perry's  own  words,  "The  function  of  the  intellect  is  the 
acquisition,  testing  and  application  of  true  beliefs.  A  belief  is  an 
anticipatory  response  set  for  a  specific  occasion,  and  its  truth  lies 
in  the  complementary  relation  between  the  response  and  the  oc- 
casion. [The  truth  of]  a  belief  is  tested  by  trying  the  response  on 
the  occasion,  or  by  trying  it  conjointly  with  other  responses  whose 
truth  is  assumed,  or  by  comparing  it  with  the  responses  of  others. ' '  " 
So  far  human  purposiveness  seems  simply  to  refer  to  "an  or- 
ganism endeavoring  to  find  its  way  in  the  midst  of  nature. ' ' 18 
But,  as  if  convinced  of  the  inadequacy  of  this  purely  biological 
point  of  view  Professor  Perry  seeks  to  do  justice  to  the  claims  of 
more  particularly  "spiritual"  interests.  "That  there  is  an  interest 
in  truth,  or  a  specifically  theoretical  activity,  which  may  assume  a 
dominant  role  in  an  individual  life,  is  a  brute  fact  of  human  be- 
havior. ' ' 19  Surely  here,  if  anywhere  in  Professor  Perry 's  system, 

is  "The  Integrity  of  the  Intellect,"  Harv.  TTieo.  Rev.,  1920,  pp.  222-3. 

i-*  Phil.  Eev.,  XXX,  2,  p.  139. 

is  Ibid.,  p.  139-40. 

i«  Ibid.,  p.  143. 

IT  Ibid.,  p.  157.     (Italics  mine.) 

18  Ibid.,  XXX,  2,  p.  140. 

is  Ibid.,  p.  139. 


578  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

we  may  hope  to  come  upon  a  distinctively  human  end.  Here  at 
last  we  shall  discover  the  mark  that  raises  man  above  the  brute, 
and  reveals  him  as  more  than  a  merely  life-desiring  physical  organ- 
ism. Here  we  shall  learn  the  true  meaning  of  the  phrase,  "it  is  the 
nature  of  the  mind  to  know."  And  we  read  on,  ".  .  .  truth  being 
the  value  which  attaches  to  a  hypothesis  or  idea  in  so  far  as  it  fits 
the  environment.  The  technique  of  induction  is  the  technique  of 
contriving  such  determinate  expectations  as  can  bear  the  ordeal  of 
empirical  fact."20 

But  this  is  only  to  repeat  what  we  had  already  learned;  the 
"independent"  activities  of  the  intellect  neatly  narrow  themselves 
until  they  fit  wholly  into  the  previously  prepared  biological  cate- 
gories in  accordance  with  the  cardinal  principle  of  attaching  cen- 
tral importance  to  the  functioning  of  the  physical  organism, — 
which  is,  after  all,  we  must  admit,  as  much  as  we  could  expect  of  a 
naturalistic  empiricism  if  it  is  to  be  self -consistent.  That  is  to  say, 
we  have  discovered  the  empirical  facts  about  human  nature,  and 
"all  in  one  place,"  as  it  was  promised  that  we  should.  Purposive- 
ness,  belief,  truth,  as  well  as  consciousness  are  construed  on  the 
basis  of  the  relation  of  the  independent,  i.e.,  merely  subjective,  in- 
dividual to  the  external  environment.  The  sole  function  of  man's 
mental  attributes  consists,  in  the  last  analysis,  in  the  fitting  of 
specific  responses  to  determinate  occasions.  And  this,  we  must 
bear  in  mind,  not  merely  for  the  more  immediate  purposes  of  natural 
science;  it  is  considered  to  be  an  ultimate  philosophical  position. 

Now  the  principal  criticism  that  may  be  directed  against  such  a 
conception  of  the  nature  of  purposiveness,  belief,  and  truth, — or  of 
mind  in  general — is,  not  that  it  is  wholly  false  to  the  facts  of  ex- 
perience, but  rather  that  it  does  not  cover  all  the  facts.  Obviously, 
however,  it  follows  from  this  objection,  if  valid,  that  Professor 
Perry's  views  do  not  adequately  account  even  for  those  facts  as- 
sumed to  be  the  sole  ones  observable  as  constituting  human  experi- 
ence. And  it  may  be  said  at  once  that  his  failure  to  do  justice  to 
the  nature  of  such  conceptions  is  largely  inherent  in  the  previously 
noted  logical  weakness  of  his  abstract,  "scientific"  method  of  inter- 
pretation of  experience.  In  the  following  paragraphs,  therefore, 
we  shall  attempt  to  indicate  some  of  the  most  obvious  shortcomings, 
as  we  see  them,  implied  in  Professor  Perry's  assumptions. 

We  have  already  pointed  out  the  abstraction  contained  in  the 
use  of  the  phrase  "external  environment,"  while  tentatively  admit- 
ting its  validity  under  certain  definite  conditions,  for  the  purposes 

aofforv.  Theol.  Bev.,  1920,  p.  228.  (Italics  mine.)  Of.  also  Present  PhVo- 
tophifol  Tendencies,  pp.  323ff. 


PROFESSOR  PERRY'S  EMPIRICISM  579 

of  science.  But  indeed  one  may  question  even  the  scientific  rele- 
vancy of  the  term,  if  it  is  taken  to  signify  pure  externality.  Yet  this 
is  apparently  its  meaning  for  Professor  Perry,  based  as  it  is  on  his 
doctrine  of  external  relations.  We  must  insist  again,  however,  that 
such  abstractions  have  no  place  in  an  ultimate  account  of  things 
such  as  philosophy  professes  to  be.  Philosophy,  if  not  science, 
must  recognize  that  man  is  not  superadded  from  the  outside  to  a 
strange  and  foreign  world ;  rather  he  is  part  and  parcel  of  his  world 
and  it  of  him.  If  now  we  find  it  necessary  to  consider  the  environ- 
ment apart  from  man's  relation  to  it,  as,  e.g.,  in  the  physical  sci- 
ences ;  or  if  we  may  profitably  consider  man  apart  from  his  environ- 
ment, a  very  doubtful  hypothesis  for  any  science,  we  have  always 
to  remember  that  ultimately  the  two  factors  are  not  independent 
but  complementary.  We  began  by  making  an  obvious  abstraction; 
we  should  conclude  by  reuniting  what  we  momentarily  tore  asunder. 
This  is  only  to  say  that  the  distinctions  which  we  make  between 
mind  as  such  and  nature  as  such  ultimately  fall  within  the  concrete 
whole  of  things. 

Granted  that  this  be  true,  it  is  obvious  that  an  attempt  to  ex- 
plain or  describe  purposiveness,  belief,  or  truth  in  terms  of  the 
relation  of  an  individual  to  an  "independent"  and  "external"  en- 
vironment, however  broad  a  sense  we  may  apply  to  the  latter  term,  is 
bound  to  result  in  failure.  At  the  very  start  of  our  attempt  to  at- 
tain an  adequate  philosophical  insight  into  the  nature  of  things  we 
prejudice  our  cause  by  limiting  our  vision  to  an  arbitrarily  speci- 
fied field  bounded  by  abstract  biological  categories. 

A  specific  example  will  perhaps  serve  to  make  clear  the  distinc- 
tion between  Professor  Perry's  views  and  those  of  a  more  satis- 
factory alternative  position.  A  human  being,  let  us  say,  is  a  physi- 
cal organism,  in  time  and  space,  composed  of  chemical  elements,  and 
possessing  a  life-history.  But  what  is  thus  true  at  certain  stages  of 
knowledge,  e.g.,  the  biological — falls  far  short  of  the  whole  truth  at 
the  stage  at  which  such  a  human  being  assumes  his  place  in  society 
as  a  member  of  a  family,  a  friend,  a  political  associate.  What  binds 
him  to  other  members  of  society  depends  in  part  upon  physical  and 
biological  conditions,  but  certainly  not  less  upon  intellectual,  esthet- 
ic and  ethical  considerations.  These  higher  phases  include  and 
transform  the  significance  of  the  lower  ones.  The  merely  external 
aspects  are  transcended,  though  preserved,  through  the  recognition 
that  mind  is  the  binding  thread  which  unites  the  particular  indi- 
viduals in  a  systematic  whole. 

In  such  a  sphere,  which,  be  it  noted,  is  only  the  rightful  herit- 
age of  man  as  a  human  being,  thought  is  not  forced  to  satisfy  its 


580  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

natural  tendency  by  seeking  identity  in  artificial  abstractions,  e.g., 
neutral  entities,  below  the  range  even  of  the  physical  sciences. 
Rather  the  difficulty  of  finding  this  identity  becomes  less  as  the 
standpoint  progressively  approaches  that  of  thinking,  rational  be- 
ings,— our  fellow-men.  Once  past  the  mechanical  standpoint  of  phys- 
ical science,  perhaps  even  in  physics,  this  bare  and  formal  identity 
begins  to  develop  within  itself  the  complementary  aspect  of  divers- 
ity— a  diversity  which  does  not  destroy  but  only  adds  to  the  rich- 
ness and  concreteness  of  the  identity. 

Prom  this  standpoint  we  may  retain,  so  far  as  valid,  Professor 
Perry's  interpretations  of  purposiveness,  belief,  and  truth,  but  it 
is  highly  important  to  recognize  that  while  retained,  they  are  also 
quite  as  surely  transcended.  For  example,  it  is  doubtlessly  true  in 
a  sense  that  the  individual  must  occupy  himself  with  the  framing 
of  "determinate"  responses  to  "specific"  occasions  in  which  he 
finds  himself  involved  in  the  round  of  daily  experience.  But  it  is 
quite  obviously  an  abstraction  to  seek  the  whole  meaning  of  his 
conduct  in  such  transient  acts.  A  life  organized  on  such  a  plane 
of  animal  existence  is  just  the  one  Socrates  cried  out  against  as  not 
fit  for  a  man  to  live.  And  besides  all  this,  there  is  to  be  accounted 
for  in  any  system  of  philosophy  worthy  of  the  name,  the  fact  of 
man's  interest  in — quite  as  they  are  for  themselves,  and  apart  from 
any  survival  value  they  may  incidentally  possess — "the  good,  the 
beautiful,  and  the  true." 

Religion,  art,  and  philosophy,  we  like  to  believe,  are  more  than 
mere  expressions  of  animal  behavior,  or  the  result  of  sentimental 
prejudice  for  idle  speculation.  They  are  ways  of  giving  utterance 
to  man's  sense  of  oneness  with,  and  of  participation  in  the  universe 
(including  of  course  the  natural  environment)  as  a  whole.  As  such 
they  possess  a  value,  a  meaning,  not  expressible,  it  is  true,  in  bio- 
logical categories  or  in  terms  of  abstract  empiricism,  but  none  the 
less  real  and  philosophically  significant  for  all  that. 

H.  R.  SMART. 

COBNKLL  UNIVERSITY. 


BEHAVIOR  AND  PURPOSE 

THROUGH  the  importance  assigned  to  objective  conditions  as 
contrasted  with  subjective,  and  to  methods  of  behavior  as 
contrasted  with  beliefs,  the  present  century  has  witnessed  the  de- 
velopment of  a  new  emphasis  in  philosophic  and  psychological  in 


BEHAVIOR  AND  PURPOSE  581 

terpretation.  We  no  longer  attribute  preeminent  importance  to  the 
individual's  conviction,  but  ask  for  objective  biography  rather 
than  for  introspective  autobiography.  Not  what  a  man  says  but 
what  he  does  gives  us  the  fruitful  insight  into  his  character;  when 
saying  and  doing  tell  different  stories  we  accept  the  latter  as  the 
faithful  record  and  call  the  former  misstatement.  Our  interest  in 
the  latter,  in  the  doing,  is  not  to  be  explained  as  getting  us  nearer 
the  truth,  since  we  may  as  correctly  ascertain  what  a  man  thought 
as  what  he  did ;  it  is  to  be  explained  as  due  to  our  feeling  that  the 
latter  method  gives  us  better  insight  into  what  is  of  most  impor- 
tance. This  method  of  interpretation  has  been  fruitful  of  results 
and  promises  even  more  than  present  performance,  indeed,  is  but 
the  threshold  of  a  new  understanding.  The  path  along  which  it 
beckons  leads  into  a  land  of  promise  whose  first  fruits  are  hearten- 
ing. But,  as  happens  with  new  points  of  view,  there  are  misunder- 
standings and  misapplications. 

The  behavioristic  view  is  sometimes  interpreted  by  its  cham- 
pions as  ruling  out  purpose  and  "ethics,"  as  being  in  itself  self-suf- 
ficient and  irreconcilable  with  our  previous  standards  of  procedure. 
We  believe  this  to  be  true  only  in  part,  and  to  a  smaller  extent  than 
is  commonly  admitted  by  the  supporters  of  behaviorism.  So  far 
from  true  is  it  that  "ethics"  is  irrelevant  to  behavior  that  one 
might  say  it  is  never  irrelevant.  The  possibility  of  reducing  all 
ethics  to  forms  of  behavior  has,  as  its  supplement  and  counterpart, 
the  possibility  of  reducing  all  behavior  to  ethics.  Analysis  of  altru- 
ism into  sympathetic  behavior  which  simply  behaves  in  that  classi- 
fiable manner  does  not  preclude  ethical  analysis  of  sympathetic  be- 
havior, nor  of  the  behavioristic  classifier. 

Behavior  is  not  just  behavior.  It  is  behavior  of  a  certain  drift 
or  drive, — otherwise  it  were  useless  to  classify  it  as  behavior. 
When  the  behaviorist  puts  forward  his  thesis  he  does  so  with  a 
purpose  in  his  behavior,  not  merely  that  he  may  behave.  Behavior 
is  not  of  equal  or  indifferent  significance.  Some  sorts  are  of  great 
importance  for  human  beings,  others  are  relatively  unimportant — 
a  truth  so  obvious  that  only  a  persistent  blindness  to  it  in  some 
quarters  can  justify  the  near  tautology.  The  test  of  behavior  should 
be  behavior  itself,  indeed,  must  be  in  terms  of  behavior.  But  by 
what  sort  of  behavior  shall  we  test  behavior?  What  shall  be  our 
standard  and  how  shall  it  apply? 

The  significance  of  behavior,  let  it  be  submitted,  must  be  ad- 
judged in  the  light,  not  of  similar  nor  of  less,  but  of  larger  and 
more  inclusive  schemes  of  behavior.  At  any  moment  my  walking 
from  my  house  to  the  letter  box  can  be  analyzed  as  putting  one  step 


582  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ahead  becau.se  the  other  is  behind,  as  a  continual  catching  myself 
from  falling  in  the  direction  in  which  my  body  is  moving,  as  an  in- 
tricate system  of  muscular  checks  and  balances  calling  into  service  an 
intricate  nervous  system  of  finely  adjusted  interactions.  Such  a 
cross-section  analysis  of  my  activity  may  be  correct  in  every  detail 
yet  be  relatively  meaningless  as  an  explanation  of  my  activity.  Its 
explanation  can  be  found  only  when  the  cross-section  is  made  length- 
wise, and  includes  my  whole  procedure  from  house  to  mail  box. 
The  significance  of  the  detailed  behavior  becomes  evident  only  in 
the  light  of  my  larger  and  more  inclusive  behavior.  This  last-men- 
tioned behavior  is,  again,  only  relatively  self -complete,  and  for  more 
complete  understanding  must  be  related  to  my  larger  schemes  of 
behavior.  In  other  words,  any  detail  of  my  behavior  is  a  phase  of 
all  my  behavior,  often  as  important  a  phase  of  my  future  behavior 
as  of  my  recent  or  remote  past. 

The  systems  of  behavior  represented  by  various  living  species 
of  animals  are  not  of  equal  import,  much  less  are  the  systems  of  be- 
havior represented  by  various  individuals  of  equal  import.  Often, 
the  significant  thing  about  the  behavior  of  an  individual  is  its 
relation  to  the  behavior  which  characterizes  his  historical  epoch 
or  his  class.  Man  as  a  species  represents  types  of  behavior  and  man  as 
a  historical  creature  represents  progressive  changes  in  types  of  be- 
havior. The  importance  we  assign  to  individual  behavior  must  de- 
pend upon  the  importance  we  assign  to  types  of  behavior.  These 
types  may  be  potential  as  well  as  actual  ones,  unrealized  as  well  as 
completed  histories. 

As  history  itself,  though  concerned  with  the  past,  can  never  be 
concerned  with  the  past  as  such,  but  must  possess  selective  insight 
and  philosophic  guidance,  so  a  psychology  concerned  with  behavior 
can  never  be  concerned  only  with  behavior.  It  must  be  concerned 
with  some  types  more  than  with  others,  with  the  significant  rather 
than  the  insignificant.  Behaviorism  is  a  point  of  view  and  must 
justify  itself  by  its  fruits.  It  can  classify  under  its  categories,  but 
must  itself  submit  to  classification.  By  whatever  behavioristic  term 
the  test  be  called,  behaviorism  must  submit  to  the  test  of  significance 
and  value. 

WILSON  D.  WALLIS. 
REID  COLLEGE. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Evolutionary   Naturalism.     ROY   WOOD   SELLARS.      Chicago:   The 
Open  Court  Publishing  Company.    1922.    Pp.  343. 
This  volume  invites  attention  as  the  first  published  attempt  to 

base  a  metaphysical  system  upon  critical  realism.    Professor  Sellars 


BOOK  REVIEWS  583 

believes  that  a  new  naturalism,  supplanting  the  older  materialism, 
is  indicated  when  the  categories  are  examined  in  the  light  of  an 
adequate  epistemology  and  when  principles  derived  from  a  study 
of  the  biological  sciences  are  given  due  importance  in  metaphysical 
explanation.  The  insufficiency  of  the  older  materialism  is  ascribed 
to  its  tendencies  to  hypostasize  scientific  concepts  and  to  reduce 
biological  to  physico-chemical  processes  without  a  remainder. 

Two  chapters  are  devoted  to  an  account  of  the  epistemological 
foundation  on  which  the  author's  metaphysics  is  based.  This  ac~ 
count  does  not  differ  from  his  earlier  writing  on  the  same  subject. 
He  maintains  that  physical  entities  are  not  objects  in  their  own 
right,  but  are  made  such  by  the  selective  activities  of  the  organism. 
Objects  are  known  by  means  of  data  in  consciousness  which,  how- 
ever, are  wholly  subjective  and  existentially  distinct  from  the  ob- 
jects known.  Thus  knowledge  is  not  intuitive,  as  idealism  and 
naive  realism  suppose,  but  mediate.  Nor  is  knowledge  obtained 
from  data  which  are  copies  of  physical  entities,  for  by  means  of  data 
we  know  objects,  not  our  subjective  states.  The  adequacy  of  cogni- 
tion rests  on  the  fact  that  nature  controls  the  knowledge-process  in 
the  interest  of  biological  adaptation.  The  categories,  therefore,  are 
truly  informative  of  the  physical  world,  for  "nature  itself  would 
need  to  change  before  they  would  become  invalid"  (p.  81). 

The  major  portion  of  the  book  is  given  over  to  discussion  of  the 
individual  categories.  It  is  emphasized  that  there  are  different 
levels  and  contexts  of  interpretation  from  sensation  to  conception 
and  abstraction,  and  that  a  true  estimate  of  the  value  for  knowledge 
of  any  category  can  be  obtained  only  by  a  genetic  consideration. 
The  author  finds  these  levels  of  interpretation  continuous  in  the 
main  and  informative  of  the  physical  world.  Thus  the  sensational 
elements  of  our  spacial  experience  connect  naturally  with  the  con- 
ceptual, and  even  abstract  mathematical  space  gives  information 
about  real  space. 

"Space  as  a  category  is  not  an  external  reality.  To  assert  that 
the  physical  world  is  spacial,  means,  not  that  the  physical  world  is 
in  a  non-dynamic  receptaculum  analogous  to  mathematical  space, 
but  that  certain  predicates  are  interpretative  of  its  actual  constitu- 
tion and  nature"  (p.  99).  These  predicates  are  found  in  judg- 
ments of  position,  relative  size,  contour,  distance,  and  direction. 
"These  elements  give  the  very  meaning  of  space  as  a  category"  (p. 
99).  In  like  manner,  "temporal  contrasts  should  not  be  read  too 
naively  into  nature"  (p.  120).  The  world  is  temporal,  rather  than 
in  time.  Sellars  subordinates  the  category  of  time  to  that  of 
change;  real  time  is  change  in  the  physical  world. 


584  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPll  Y 

In  his  treatment  of  things  and  their  properties,  the  author 
reaches  the  conclusion  that  the  distinction  between  substance  and 
properties  is  epistemological  rather  than  ontological.  A  substance 
is  the  subject  of  predication  in  a  judgment.  Hence  it  was  sup- 
posed that  there  was  a  unitary  and  unknowable  substance  support- 
ing properties.  The  true  view,  however,  is  that  properties  are 
simply  the  elements  of  our  tested  thought  of  the  thing.  Things  are 
(partially)  their  known  properties.  All  sense-data  are  materials 
for  knowledge;  all  qualities  are  contentually  subjective;  the  dis- 
tinction between  primary  and  secondary  qualities  rests  on  either  an 
intuitional  view  of  knowledge  or  a  naive  copy-theory.  Qualities 
and  quantities  are  not  opposed ;  colors,  tastes,  and  odors,  as  well  as 
shape  and  size,  are  indicative  of  physical  conditions.  But  "in  no 
case  is  there  assumed  to  be  a  resemblance  between  a  sense-datum 
and  its  external  cause.  What  does  hold  is  an  ordered  correlation 
so  that  to  every  difference  in  the  one  there  is  a  difference  in  the 
other  manifold.  It  is  because  of  this  ordered  correlation  that  we 
are  able  to  infer  the  size,  structure,  behavior,  position  and  internal 
constitution  of  physical  objects"  (p.  188). 

The  evolutionary  naturalist  is  a  pluralist  and  is  sympathetic 
with  the  doctrine  of  external  relations  as  against  logical  monism. 
He  finds,  however,  both  continuities  and  discontinuities  in  nature, 
and  he  maintains  that  the  question  whether  any  particular  relation 
is  internal  or  external  is  to  be  decided  solely  on  empirical  evidence. 
Many  biological  relations  are  internal,  and  the  character  of  their 
terms  has  become  modified  from  the  time  when  they  entered  into 
relation.  Relations  themselves  must  not  be  reified;  there  are  terms 
in  relation,  not  relations  and  terms. 

Russell's  mathematical  analysis  of  motion,  while  defended,  is 
declared  not  to  be  exhaustive.  Motion,  for  Professor  Sellars,  is  a 
case  of  behavior  implying  energetics,  and  back  of  motion  lies  force. 
He  recognizes  that  if  we  use  the  concept  of  force  as  a  principle  of 
explanation  instead  of  passing  to  a  quantitative  description  of  its 
manifestations,  we  shall  get  nowhere,  but  he  says  that  the  limita- 
tions of  our  knowledge  should  not  be  permitted  to  empty  reality 
of  any  content  for  which  we  have  an  empirical  basis.  (One  may 
question  whether  he  has  been  equally  scrupulous  in  respect  to  the 
empirical  content  of  colors  and  odors.)  We  are  urged  irresistibly 
to  the  positing  of  force  in  objects  by  our  fundamental  realistic  be- 
lief that  bodies  are  something  in  themselves  and  have  a  determinate 
nature.  But  it  is  not  admissible  to  follow  idealism  in  its  belief  that 
the  activity  which  we  experience  in  consciousness  is  the  only  type 
of  activity  in  nature. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  585 

We  must  avoid  interpreting  the  world  in  terms  of  human 
agency,  as  well  as  the  tendency  to  reduce  causality  to  logical  im- 
plication. Like  other  categories,  causality  is  informative  of  reality. 
Causality  is  more  than  sequence,  more  even  than  a  uniformity  of 
sequence.  It  tells  us  that  change  is  not  adventitious,  but  that  it 
''grows  out  of  the  very  heart  of  that  which  changes.  But,  if  so, 
change  throws  light  upon  the  nature  of  the  changing  system;  it  is 
the  kind  of  a  system  to  produce  this  change  as  an  end-term"  (p. 
248).  A  scientific  treatment  of  causality  as  opposed  to  a  naive 
view  seeks  to  appreciate,  not  two  factors,  but  all  the  factors  at  work. 
Causality  is  not  purely  temporal ;  it  is  spacial  as  well,  and  it  signi- 
fies the  activity  of  a  changing  system. 

Freedom,  treated  in  the  manner  made  familiar  by  the  writings 
of  Windelband  and  others,  is  reconciled  with  determinism  by  analy- 
sis of  the  meaning  of  these  concepts.  These  attempts  fail  alike  to 
explain  the  crucial  instance  of  the  exercise  of  freedom  when  the 
self  is  "divided."  Novelty  is  regarded  as  descriptive  of  the  evolu- 
tionary process,  but  not  as  in  conflict  with  continuity.  From  Pro- 
fessor Sellars'  own  standpoint,  I  can  not  but  feel  that  novelty 
would  find  more  satisfactory  interpretation  as  a  subjective  category. 
If  real  time  is  change  in  the  physical  world,  novelty  would  be  a 
concept  that  we  would  apply  to  the  succeeding  state  as  compared 
with  the  former,  when  there  was  a  striking  alteration  in  data.  Em- 
pirical teleology  is  defended.  It  is  especially  apparent  in  organ- 
isms, where  each  organ  has  its  function  which  assists  in  the  work- 
ing of  the  whole.  "This  ordering  is  maintained  by  structural  and 
functional  coordinations"  (p.  337).  We  must  be  careful  not  to 
inject  naive  anthropomorphism  into  the  concept,  but  on  the  other 
hand  we  must  not  underestimate  the  physical  world.  The  chapter 
which  deals  with  mechanism  and  teleology  is  especially  vague  and 
inconclusive. 

The  fact  that  the  structure  of  consciousness  reflects  the  position 
and  adjustments  of  the  organism  suggests  that  there  is  no  exist- 
ential independence  of  consciousness  from  the  brain.  The  burden 
of  proof  that  there  is  a  separation  rests  upon  dualism.  "Evolu- 
tionary naturalism  does  not  believe  that  the  higher  levels  of  nature 
are  purely  mechanical;  it  accepts  critical  points  with  resultant 
new  properties"  (p.  292).  "Who  has  a  right  to  say  a  priori  how 
great  a  novelty  may  arise  and  so  set  limits  to  the  possibilities  of 
nature?"  (p.  297).  The  author  describes  his  view  as  a  develop- 
ment of  the  double-aspect  theory  based  on  critical  realism  (p. 
294).  Consciousness,  however,  is  not  an  aspect  of  the  whole  physi- 
cal world,  but  a  novel  aspect  of  brain-activity,  functional  in  char- 


586  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

acter.  The  biological  sciences  indicate  that  an  organized  system 
is  more  than  the  sum  of  its  parts,  and  that  a  whole  may  exert  con- 
trol over  its  parts.  Thus  consciousness  is  efficacious.  The  brain 
is  "a  stream  of  tendencies  lit  up  by  consciousness"  (p.  316).  "The 
contents  of  consciousness  are  correlative  to  neural  processes  which 
are  not  found  at  the  inorganic  level.  They  come  and  go,  and  yet, 
as  memory  shows,  they  are  not  completely  lost.  .  .  .  The  differ- 
ence between  the  conscious  and  the  unconscious  must  be  one  of  de- 
gree and  not  of  kind"  (p.  318). 

Critical  realism  steers  a  middle  course  between  skepticism  and 
intuit  ionism.  When  a  critical  realist  seeks  to  build  a  metaphysical 
system  in  harmony  with  his  epistemology,  one  is  interested  in  watch- 
ing how  far  his  faith  will  carry  him.  Faith  here  is  acceptance  of 
data  as  revelatory.  The  question  arises  (and  the  answer  given 
will  vary  with  the  individual  thinker),  what  aspects  of  the  consci- 
ous content  shall  be  accepted  as  mediating  knowledge  of  a  reality 
beyond  the  knower?  Professor  Sellars  finds  his  answer  to  this 
question  in  his  faith  in  the  results  of  the  special  sciences,  the 
achievements  of  enlightened  common-sense.  That  he  is  not  en- 
tirely successful  from  the  metaphysical  standpoint  is  partly  due  to 
the  limits  which  bound  his  faith.  But  one  wishes  that  he  had 
broadened  somewhat  his  own  method  of  investigation.  He  is  so 
deeply  interested  in  inquiring  about  the  nature  of  the  physical 
world  that  it  has  not  occurred  to  him  that  a  correlative  study  is 
that  of  the  characteristics  peculiar  to  conscious  processes.  He  has 
studied  the  character  of  data  only  in  reference  to  their  cognitive 
value.  Now  science  reaches  knowledge  that  is  formal  in  character. 
And  the  knowledge  of  the  physical  world  which  Professor  Sellars 
defends  is,  correspondingly,  a  knowledge  of  "size,  structure,  be- 
havior, position,  and  internal  constitution  of  physical  objects." 
But  he  has  not  explained  by  a  study  of  the  conscious  process  the 
reason  why  knowledge  is  thus  limited.  He  has  chosen  rather,  ex- 
cept perhaps  in  his  treatment  of  force,  to  ignore  the  fact  that  physi- 
cal science  can  not  do  without  a  fundamental  substance,  whether 
ether  or  electricity,  and  to  assimilate  naively  substance  and  quality 
to  structure. 

While  this  mode  of  procedure  is  not  entirely  unconvincing  in 
his  discussion  of  the  inorganic,  it  encounters  vast  difficulties  when 
he  comes  to  treat  the  mind-body  problem.  Here  the  only  correla- 
tions of  which  he  can  speak  are  those  of  structure  and  function. 
The  warm,  sensuous  characteristics  of  conscious  qualities  have  not 
been  anticipated  by  a  slow  evolution  of  substance.  They  burst  out 
of  structural  properties  in  a  way  that  Professor  Sellars  can  de- 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  587 

scribe  only  by  the  word  "novelty."  We  must  not  indeed  "set 
limits  to  the  possibilities  of  nature,"  but  reason  herself  sets  certain 
limits  beyond  which  she  encounters  the  irrational.  If,  as  the  author 
himself  avers,  in  conscious  activity  alone  we  are  "on  the  inside," 
evolutionary  naturalism  might  lead  more  readily  in  the  direction 
of  pan-psychism  or  Haeckel's  monism.  Either  of  the  latter  would 
afford  a  better  escape  from  dualism — which,  of  course,  is  equally 
compatible  with  critical  realism. 

Professor  Sellars  is  to  be  commended  in  his  attempt  to  square 
critical  realism  with  naturalism.  His  writing  suffers,  however, 
from  a  disorderly  style.  The  headings  and  sub-headings  of  the  in- 
dividual chapters  are  clear,  but  their  matter  often  reads  like  a 
note-book,  rather  than  like  a  finished  treatise.  This  fault  is  un- 
fortunate in  an  age  when  philosophers  are  striving  to  reach  mutual 
understanding. 

MAURICE  PICAED. 
NEW  YORK  CITY. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  BULLETIN.  Vol.  19,  No.  6.  June,  1922. 
The  Psychology  of  Taste  and  Smell:  E.  A.  McC.  Gamble.  Flight 
of  Colors  in  the  After  Image  of  a  Bright  Light :  W.  Berry.  Cutane- 
ous Space:  H.  E.  Burtt. 

JOURNAL  OF  EXPERIMENTAL  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  V,  No.  4.  August, 
1922.  Individual  Variations  in  Retinal  Sensitivity,  and  their  Corre- 
lation with  Ophthalmologic  Findings:  P.  W.  C0&6.  Adult  Tests 
of  the  Stanford  Revision  Applied  to  University  Faculty  Members: 
H.  H.  Caldwell.  Cumulative  Correlation:  J.  C.  Chapman.  Learn- 
ing when  Frequency  and  Recency  Factors  are  Negative:  J.  Peter* 
son. 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW.  Vol.  29,  No.  5.  September,  1922.  Be- 
havior and  the  Central  Nervous  System :  A.  P.  Weiss.  How  are  Our 
Instincts  Acquired  ?  Zing  T.  Kuo.  Intelligence  and  Learning :  J. 
Peterson.  The  Organismal  Point  of  View  in  the  Study  of  Motor 
and  Mental  Learning :  J.  A.  Melrose. 

REVISTA  DE  FILOSOFLV.  Vol.  VIII,  No.  V.  September,  1922. 
Amadeo  Jacques:  A.  N.  Ponce.  El  monismo  estetico  de  Vascon- 
celos:  G.  P.  Troconis.  La  historia  de  un  ciencia:  R.  A.  Orgaz. 
El  pensamiento  de  Juan  Montalvo:  F.  Cordova.  El  progreso  y 
los  espacios  de  tiempo :  A  Spinelli.  Antecedentes  de  la  filosof fa  en 
Bolivia :  D.  Eyzaguirre.  Ensenanza  de  la  filosof  fa  en  Bolivia :  C. 
Lopez.  Merito,  Tiempo,  Estilo:  J.  Ingenieros. 


588  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

JOURNAL  OP  EDUCATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  XIII,  No.  6.  Bep- 
tember,  1922.  An  Experiment  in  Learning  an  Abstract  Subject: 
E.  L.  Thorndike  and  E.  A.  Lincoln.  A  Class  Experiment  in  Learn- 
ing: W.  F.  Dearborn  and  E.  A.  Lincoln.  Language  Error  Tests: 
6.  M.  Wilson.  Some  Evidence  of  an  Adolescent  Increase  in  the 
Rate  of  Mental  Growth :  K.  Murdoch  and  L.  R.  Sullivan.  Tentative 
Order  of  Difficulty  of  the  Terman  Vocabulary  with  Very  Young 
Children:  M.  V.  Cobb.  Some  Retests  with  the  Stanford-Binet 
Scale:  K.  Gordon.  "The  Constancy  of  the  IQ"  again:  F.  M. 
Teagarten. 

Aliotta,  Antonio:  Relativismo  e  Idealismo.  Naples:  F.  Per- 
rella.  1922.  99  pp. 

Aristoteles:  Lehre  vom  Beweis — oder  Zweite  Analytik.  A  new 
translation  with  an  introduction  by  T.  E.  Rolfes.  Leipzig:  Felix 
Meiner.  1922.  163  pp. 

Kant,  Immanuel:  Vermischte  Schriften.  With  Introduction 
and  Notes  by  Karl  Vorlander.  Leipzig:  Felix  Meiner.  1922. 
324  pp. 

McTaggart,  J.  McT.  E. :  Studies  in  the  Hegelian  Dialectic.  New 
York:  Macmillan  Co.  1922.  2nd  edition,  xvi  +  254  pp. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

Professor  A.  N.  Whitehead  of  Cambridge  University  has  been 
elected  president  of  the  Aristotelian  Society  for  the  coming  season. 
His  inaugural  address  will  be  delivered  on  November  6th. 

Dr.  Henry  H.  Goddard,  former  director  of  the  State  Bureau  of 
Juvenile  Research  at  Columbus,  Ohio,  has  been  called  to  a  professor- 
ship in  abnormal  psychology  at  Ohio  State  University. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  22  OCTOBER  26,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


IN  isolating  the  logical  aspects  of  "Critical  Kealism"  as  set  forth 
in  the  recent  volume  of  essays  under  this  caption,  certain  ob- 
stacles are  early  encountered.  First,  there  are  numerous  and  im- 
portant differences  of  opinion  among  the  writers  which  makes  it 
difficult  to  reach  a  common  doctrine.  Second,  the  discussions  of 
knowledge  are  confined  almost  entirely  to  perception.  Keeping 
strictly  to  perception,  we  could  hardly  expect  it  to  carry  us  very 
far  into  logical  operations.  Still,  for  critical  realism  perception  is 
knowledge;  and  though  it  involves  no  inference,  it  has  the  char- 
acter of  "truth,"  or  "error,"  to  which  a  special  chapter  is  devoted. 
In  the  role  of  knowledge  and  with  the  capacity  for  truth  and  error, 
perception,  while  held  to  be  "immediate,"  gets  to  be  a  very  highly 
mediated  case  of  immediacy,  requiring  a  lot  of  logical  machinery 
to  run  it. 

Indeed,  to  my  mind  we  have  here  that  first  disobedience, 
which  is  the  source  of  so  much  subsequent  logical  and  epistemologi- 
cal  woe;  namely,  the  confusion  of  the  entities  and  machinery  of 
logical  operations  with  the  familiar  things  of  immediate 
experience.  It  is  the  old,  old  sin  of  the  reflective  fallacy,  the 
logician's  vanity,  which  has  dogged  philosophy  from  the  beginning. 
As  soon  as  we  acquire  a  little  reflective  capacity  and  machinery 
we  are  like  a  farmer  with  a  new  grinding  machine,  who  wants  to 
run  everything  on  the  place  through  it,  until  even  the  members  of 
the  family  are  in  danger. 

This  generates  a  double  set  of  difficulties.  It  reduces  immedi- 
ate experience,  or,  to  use  the  critical  realist's  term,  the  given,  to 
the  impoverished  state  of  an  hypostatized  logical  function  called 
"essence,"  with  the  result  that  this  emaciated  given  has  to  be  sur- 
reptitiously fed  up  as  the  exposition  proceeds.  On  the  other  hand, 
it  forces  logical  operations  and  categories  in  their  attempt  to  play 
the  role  of  immediate  experience  to  become  a  hybrid  sort  of  meta- 
physical entity,  half  subsistent  and  half  existent,  with  little  pros- 
pect of  ever  reaching  their  own  goal  of  truth  and  error. 

589 


.-><)<)  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

In  perceptual  knowledge,  we  are  told,  there  are  three  funda- 
mental factors.  First,  the  given,  the  datum.  This  can  not  be  an 
existence,  physical  or  psychical,  else,  so  runs  the  tale,  there  is  no 
place  for  error.  It  must  then  be  a  subsistential,  logical  essence. 
Second,  there  is  an  existential  "mental  state"  which  is  the 
"carrier,"  the  "vehicle"  of  the  essences.  In  passing,  we  may  note 
that  the  critical  realist  does  not  seem  at  all  disturbed  by  the  troubles 
which  the  Greeks  encountered  in  thinking  of  a  subsistential  essence 
as  a  passenger  in  an  existential  taxi.  Third,  there  is  the  physical 
object  of  which  essences  are  "instinctively"  and  "irresistibly"  af- 
firmed. 

Such  is  the  official  cast  of  the  characters  in  the  drama  of  per- 
ceptual knowledge.  Whereupon  someone  may  say  that  so  simple 
a  plot  for  a  one-act  play  scarcely  warrants  the  charge  of  complica- 
tions and  entanglements.  But  those  of  you  who  have  followed  the 
text  will  agree,  I  think,  that  we  do  not  get  very  far  before  we  dis- 
cover that  the  official  cast  and  plot  is  really  only  a  part  of  one 
scene.  For  it  becomes  evident,  at  once,  that  one  of  the  star  per- 
formers— it  is  a  little  uncertain  whether  it  is  the  hero  or  the  vil- 
lain— is  left  out  of  the  official  cast  altogether;  namely,  the  bodily 
organism  of  the  knower.  For  we  are  told  that  not  only  do  mental 
states,  but  the  very  constitution  of  the  given  essence,  depend  on  the 
bodily  organism.  As  the  plot  thickens,  we  note,  too,  that  some  of 
the  other  characters  begin  to  assume  new  roles.  The  mental  states 
which  at  the  beginning  are  simply  "vehicles"  for  the  essences  soon, 
like  Locke's  cabinet  and  sheet  of  paper,  begin  to  do  strange  things 
for  vehicles.  They  perform  operations  which  the  authors  call  "as- 
sociating," "willing,"  "having  an  interest,"  "turning  the  atten- 
tion," etc.  One  writer  speaks  of  turning  on  and  off  the  searchlight. 
The  image  of  a  psychical  taxi  turning  its  own  headlights  on  its  own 
passengers  is  engaging.  Whether  the  lights  are  properly  dimmed 
is  not  stated:  but  it  doesn't  stop  with  turning  on  and  off  the 
lights.  It  begins  to  take  liberties  with  its  subsistential  passenger. 
For  we  are  told  that  the  total  character  of  the  passenger  (the  es- 
sence) depends  on  associative  operations  of  the  vehicle  (i.e.,  mental 
states)  as  well  as  on  the  constitution  of  the  bodily  organism. 

Not  to  overwork  the  figure,  it  is  obvious,  I  think,  that  the  vari- 
ous problems  of  this  account  of  perceptual  knowledge  center  about 
the  origin  and  nature  and  function  of  these  essences  in  their  rela- 
tion to  the  other  three  main  factors,  the  mental  states,  the  bodily 
organism,  and  the  physical  object.  On  the  one  hand,  in  many  state- 
ments, especially  of  Santayana,  to  whom  Professor  Strong  says  he 
owes  the  "precious"  conception  of  essence,  these  data  seem  to  be 


SOME  ASPECTS  OF  CRITICAL  REALISM  591 

detached,  floating,  subsistential  essences  quite  in  the  Platonic  and 
neo-realistic  sense.  They  include  all  possible  qualities  and  com- 
plexes of  qualities,  primary,  secondary,  and  tertiary.  These  seem 
to  appear  in  the  mental  state  on  the  occasion  of  certain  activities 
of  the  bodily  organism,  which  may  or  may  not  be  a  response  to  the 
stimulus  of  the  physical  object  perceived  according  as  the  percep- 
tion is  veridical  or  illusory.  When  the  perception  is  "true,"  the 
essence  given  in  the  mental  state  is  identical  with  the  essence  of  the 
physical  object.  Thus,  in  the  case  of  veridical  perception,  the  es- 
sence has  two  loci,  it  rides  simultaneously  in  two  "vehicles,"  the 
mental  state  and  the  physical  object. 

On  the  other  hand,  we  find  such  statements  as  this:  "Percep- 
tual error  is  possible  because  data,  that  is  the  essences,  are  directly 
dependent  on  the  individual  organism,  not  on  the  external  object, 
varying  in  their  character,  with  the  constitution  of  the  sense  organs, 
and  the  way  in  which  these  are  effected."  Such  passages  might  be 
charged  to  careless  composition,  the  meaning  intended  being  that 
the  appearance  of  the  essence  depends  on  the  organism.  But  there 
is  the  phrase,  "varying  in  their  character  with  the  constitution  of 
the  sense  organs."  Moreover,  three  of  the  group,  Lovejoy,  Pratt, 
and  Sellers,  insist  that  the  essences  are  not  floating,  nomadic  en- 
tities, but  are  the  characters  of  the  mental  states  themselves,  and  as 
such  are  existential,  not  subsistential.1 

But  how  far  is  this  determination  of  essence  by  the  bodily  or- 
ganism and  the  mental  states  to  be  carried?  and  just  what  then  is 
to  be  their  relation  as  so  constituted  to  the  physical  object  ?  In  the 
first  essay,  Drake  says,  "It  is  the  thesis  of  this  volume  that  in  so 
far  as  perception  gives  us  accurate  knowledge,  it  does  so  by  caus- 
ing the  actual  characteristics  of  objects  to  appear  to  us.  "In  so  far 
as, ' '  but  how  far  is  this  1  Drake 's  answer  is  that  the  essences  which 
we  refer  to  the  world  about  us,  are  not  really  there,  except  in  so 
far  as  they  really  were  there  before  perception  took  place.  And 
(this  is  the  interesting  clause)  "so  far  as  secondary  and  tertiary 
qualities  and  most  of  the  primary  qualities,  they  are  never  there 
at  all ! "  One  may  well  rub  his  eyes  over  this  passage.  It  is  cer- 
tainly queer-looking  realism.  Over  and  over  we  are  told  that  it  is 
the  heart  of  the  doctrine  of  realism  that  the  what  of  the  object, 
that  is,  its  qualities  and  character,  are  given  in  the  essences.  But 
when  all  the  secondary  and  tertiary,  and  most  of  the  primary  qual- 
ities are  thrown  out  of  the  what,  we  begin  to  wonder  just  what 
"what"  is  left.  The  situation  recalls  a  scene  in  the  play  "Happy- 

i  Prof essor  Sellers'  repeated  references  to  the  essences  as  "subjective," 
must  be  a  source  of  great  distress  to  Santayana. 


592  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

go-lucky"  in  which  a  tipsy  English  constable  is  making  an  invoice 
in  bankruptcy  of  dilapidated  furniture.  Standing  before  an 
unusually  rickety  piece,  he  makes  this  entry,  "One  wot-not, 
more  not  than  wot."  Drake  doesn't  say  what  this  poor  remnant 
of  a  "wot"  is.  Sellers,  who  is  less  cautious,  ventures  to 
give  a  list.  He  says  that  "time,  space,  structure,  causal  relations, 
behavior,  are  the  only  essences  which  can  belong  to  the  object  in 
case  of  veridical  perception. ' '  This  is  a  fairly  substantial  list.  But 
as  Drake  doubtless  foresaw,  its  difficulties  are  proportionately  nu- 
merous. First,  it  is  important  to  observe  that  Sellers  puts  time  as 
well  as  space  into  the  essence,  into  the  content,  of  the  physical  ob- 
ject, as  distinguished  from  its  existence.  With  time  and  space  and 
all  the  primary  qualities  put  into  the  "essence,"  what  is  left  to 
constitute  the  "existence"  of  the  object?  The  neo-realists  have 
always  carefully,  if  somewhat  dogmatically,  reserved  space  and  time, 
as — to  speak  in  a  paradox — the  essence  of  existence.  But  what  is 
an  existence  that  is  neither  of  nor  in  time  and  space?  How  does  it 
differ  from  subsistence?  Further,  if  time  and  space,  and  the  pri- 
mary qualities  are  essences,  what  is  the  difference  between  the  physi- 
cal object  as  physical,  and  the  mental  state?  The  difference  can't 
lie  in  existence,  for  the  mental  state  is  as  much  an  existence  (what- 
ever that  now  means)  as  the  physical  object.  If  it  be  said  that, 
while  the  primary  qualities  are  given  in  the  mental  state,  they  are 
not  given  as  its  essence  but  as  the  essence  of  the  physical  object, 
we  can  only  ask  again  since  time  and  space  have  been  transferred  to 
essence,  what  constitutes  the  ' '  physicality ' '  of  the  physical  object  ?  2 
But,  conceding  a  physical  object  of  some  sort,  and  essences  that 
may  somehow  "belong"  to  the  physical  object,  how  do  we  determine 
when  they  do  and  when  they  do  not  belong.  This  is  of  course  the 
question  of  truth  and  error.  Next  to  the  longest  chapter  in  the 
book  is  devoted  to  error.  But  most  of  the  chapter  is  occupied  with 
difficulties  in  other  theories,  a  little  of  it  to  the  formal  definition  of 
truth  as  consisting  in  identity  of  the  essence  in  mental  states  with 
the  essence  in  a  physical  object,  and  practically  none  to  the  ques- 
tion of  how  we  find  out  whether  and  when  these  objects  do  really 

*  In  the  midst  of  such  questions  as  these  the  reader  is  obliged  to  return  often 
for  reassurance  to  the  closing  sentence  of  the  preface,  which  says,  "We  have 
found  it  entirely  possible  to  isolate  the  problem  of  Knowledge"  (i.e.,  from  meta- 
physics). In  the  midst  of  his  struggle  with  these  questions,  which  multiply  at 
a  terrific  rate,  in  dealing  with  the  problem  of  introspection,  Drake  wistfully 
says,  "The  writer  has  his  own  ontological  views,  the  exposition  of  which  would 
clear  up  this  whole  situation!"  For  this  boon  I  am  sure  most  readers  would 
gladly  absolve  Professor  Drake  from  his  oath,  however  solemn,  to  avoid  meta- 
physics. (Italics  mine.) 


SOME  ASPECTS  OF  CRITICAL  REALISM  593 

have  them.  In  view  of  all  the  hard  things  said  by  critical  realists 
about  the  ' '  copy-theory ' '  of  naive  realism  and  the  ' '  identity ' '  theory 
of  neo-realism  and  idealism,  the  definition  of  the  nature  of  truth 
as  consisting  in  identity  of  essences,  or  of  the  reproduction,  in  a 
mental  state  of  the  essence  of  the  physical  object,  has  a  queer  look. 
To  be  sure,  we  are  assured  early  and  often  that  the  true  and  proper 
object  of  perception  is  not  the  essence,  but  the  physical  object, 
which  is  not  to  be  thought  of  as  at  all  "like"  the  essence.  But 
while  the  object  of  perception  must  remain  unlike  the  essence  we 
get  truth  only  in  so  far  as  the  latter  "reproduces"  and  is  identical 
with  the  essence  of  the  physical  object.  The  essence  must  be  un- 
like its  object,  but  it  can  be  true  only  as  it  is  not  only  like  but 
identical  with  the  essence  of  the  object.  This  implies  that  the  "ob- 
ject ' '  is  different  from  its  own  qualities,  which  means  that,  through- 
out the  entire  discussion  the  term  "physical  object"  should  stand 
for  nothing  but  the  bare  and  empty  concept  of  existence — an  ex- 
istence which  has  not  even  spatial  or  temporal  character — since 
these  belong  to  essence. 

It  is  as  easy  to  lay  down  a  formal  definition  of  truth  as  of  any- 
thing else.  It  is  quite  another  matter  to  show  what  we  can  do 
with  it,  and  how  the  requirements  of  the  definition  can  be  met. 
If  we  search  elsewhere  than  in  the  essay  on  "error"  for  an  answer 
to  these  questions,  we  get  this  meager  response  from  Pratt :  ' '  When 
the  question  of  veridical  or  illusory  perception  arises,  first  of  all, 
one  appeals  from  one  of  the  senses  to  the  others  to  see  whether 
they  confirm  one  another.  Second,  we  may  appeal  to  other  persons ; 
third,  we  may  watch  the  supposed  object  function.  If  it  works  out 
consistently  with  our  own  experience,  and  the  experience  of  others, 
we  may  conclude  that  there  is  a  real  object."  How  far  this  is  short 
of  an  answer  to  the  problem  appears  when  we  recall  that  these  for- 
mulas are  used  by  all  theories  alike  and  mean  nothing  until  we  go  on 
to  show  in  detail  how  they  can  be  applied  to  the  particular  definition 
and  description  of  knowledge  which  we  have  laid  down.  In  the 
case  of  critical  realism,  the  question  is  how  can  these  three  tests  be 
applied  to  knowledge  defined  as  identity  of  essence  appearing  in  a 
mental  state  with  the  essence  of  a  physical  object.  Take  the  first 
test — the  appeal  from  one  sense  to  others.  Keeping  in  mind  that 
sense  qualities  are  essences,  when  we  pass  to  another  sense  we 
simply  pass  to  another  essence.  Now  how  can  piling  up  any  num- 
ber of  additional  essences  establish  the  existence  of  any  one  of 
them,  if  there  is  no  existence  to  start  with?  When  Pratt  speaks  of 
appealing  from  one  sense  to  another,  he,  along  with  us,  has  in  mind 
the  ordinary  and  salutary  experiences  of  appealing  from  our  ears 


594  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

and  noses  to  our  eyes,  from  our  eyes  to  our  hands,  and  so  on.  But 
we  have  to  remember  that  in  the  theory  we  are  discussing  "all  the 
secondary  qualities"  and  "most  of  the  primary  qualities"  are  out 
of  court  on  this  appeal,  since  they  never  are  existential.  The  ap- 
peal to  other  senses  and  other  persons  must  then  be  confined  to  a 
remnant  of  the  primary  qualities.  For  example,  in  the  case  of  ap- 
peal from  our  noses  to  our  eyes,  we  should  first  have  to  filter  out 
all  of  the  secondary  qualities,  that  is,  the  quality  and  intensity  of 
the  odor  and  reduce  the  smell  to  its  spacial  and  temporal  form, 
whatever  that  would  be,  and  then  repeat  the  performance  with  vision 
to  which  we  appeal.  How  far  this  is  from  what  actually  occurs 
when  we  make  these  appeals  is,  I  take  it,  sufficiently  obvious.  It 
is  equally  obvious  that  the  appeal  to  other  persons  does  not  touch 
the  real  question  at  issue,  which  is,  how  they  and  we  alike  reach  a 
decision  on  this  question  of  the  identity  of  essences.  As  for  the 
third  test,  consistency  with  the  rest  of  experience,  this,  for  critical 
realism,  can  scarcely  be  more  than  a  summary  of  the  other  two— 
that  is,  the  appeal  to  the  other  senses  and  to  other  persons.  And 
even  if  it  involves  anything  more  than  this,  the  question  is  what 
kind  of  consistency  can  furnish  evidence  for  this  identity  of  es- 
sences? Once  more  in  raising  these  difficulties,  I  am  not  challeng- 
ing these  time-honored  teste.  On  the  contrary,  assuming  their 
value,  the  challenge  is  on  the  definition  of  knowledge  which  it  is 
supposed  they  can  test;  it  is  on  their  availability  as  tests  of  truth 
defined  as  identity  of  essences. 

As  said  at  the  outset,  all  these  difficulties  flow  from  the  initial 
mistake  of  confusing  logical  and  non-logical  experience,  or  if  you 
shy  at  the  term  "experience,"  let  us  say  logical  and  non-logical 
things  or  affairs.  The  theory  starts  with  the  thesis  that  what  is 
given  is  simply  a  bare  subsistential  essence.  Then  we  find:  that 
the  essence  is  domiciled  in  an  existent  mental  state ;  that  it  is  condi- 
tioned by  the  constitution  of  the  bodily  organism;  that  it  is  af- 
firmed— (Sellers) — "through  the  very  pressure  and  suggestion  of 
experience,"  and — (Santayana) — "through  the  assault,  the  strain, 
the  emphasis,  the  prolongation  of  our  life  toward  the  not  given," — 
involving  such  things  as  interest  and  will  and  other  persons,  and 
yet  none  of  these  things  are  supposed  to  be  given.  No  existence 
can  be  given.  There  is  no  doubt  that  this  situation  is  "critical"; 
but  is  it  "realistic"! 

It  is  of  course  this  complete  evisceration  of  the  given,  this  re- 
duction of  it  to  a  pale,  impalpable  essence  that  still  leaves  critical 
realism  in  the  toils  of  the  epistemological  problem,  which  is  just 
the  problem  of  the  "leap,"  to  use  Santayana 's  term,  from  subsis- 


SOME  ASPECTS  OF  CRITICAL  REALISM  595 

tence  to  existence.  But  why  set  the  stage  for  this  spectacular 
"leap."  Realism,  "neo-"  and  ' 'critical,"  needs  to  become  more 
realistic ;  it  needs  to  make  a  truly  realistic  start  with  existence.  In 
so  doing,  it  would  at  once  be  on  good  terms  with  that  "common 
sense"  to  which  it  appeals  when  it  talks  of  "the  physical  object," 
and  from  which  it  appeals  when  it  talks  of  "essences."  That  it 
really  does  start  with  existences,  such  as  bodily  organisms,  mental 
images,  urges,  strains,  other  persons  and  things,  as  given,  must  be, 
I  think,  now  perfectly  obvious.  In  an  astonishing  passage,  in  his 
section  on  the  biological  truths  of  critical  realism,  Santayana  ex- 
plicitly utters  this.  He  says:  "That  this  object — (that  is,  the 
physical  object) — exists  in  a  known  space  and  time,  and  has  trace- 
able physical  relations  with  all  other  physical  objects,  is  given  from 
the  beginning.  It  is  given  in  the  fact  that  we  can  point  to  it."8 
How  can  the  official  doctrine  of  the  volume  stand  alongside  this 
passage,  indeed,  alongside  the  whole  section?  Yet  at  the  close  of 
the  next  section,  on  "the  logical  proof,"  Santayana  writes: 
"Knowledge  has  two  stages  or  leaps,  one  the  leap  of  intuition,  from 
the  state  of  the  living  organism,  to  the  consciousness  of  some  es- 
sence; and  second,  the  leap  of  faith  and  action  from  this  essence  to 
some  ulterior  existing  object."  But  in  the  passage  just  quoted  the 
second  "leap"  comes  first;  and  wipes  out  the  first  "leap";  for  the 
physical  object  in  space  and  time  "is  given  from  the  beginning." 
But  some  one  may  ask,  if  we  begin  with  existence  as  given,  where 
is  the  place  for  error?  Now,  if  we  were  supposed  to  begin  with  all 
existence,  or  with  a  static,  fixed  existence,  the  question  would  be 
pertinent  and  embarrassing.  But  if  we  assume  that  we  begin  only 
with  some  existence  which  is  also  a  changing  existence,  and  that 
we  as  also  existents  have  the  capacity  to  determine  in  some  measure 
the  direction  and  character  of  this  change,  we  need  not  be  alarmed 
at  the  prospect  of  losing  the  possibility  of  making  mistakes.  It 
should  go  without  saying  that  these  existencies  with  which  we  begin 
are  not  the  ultimate  elements  of  physics,  or  biology,  or  psychology, 
or  any  other  particular  science,  nor  are  they  "physical"  or 
"mental,"  or  "true"  or  "false."  So  to  take  them,  is  again  to  fall 
into  the  reflective  fallacy.  But  whenever  any  given  existence  is 
used  to  get  some  other  existence,  then  it  begins  to  take  on  the  charac- 
ter and  function  of  a  logical  essence.  It  no  longer  exists  for  itself 
as  the  object  of  admiration  or  fear  or  love  or  hate.  It  no  longer 
holds  the  center  of  the  stage,  but  has  become  now  a  means,  a  basis 
of  inference,  to  another  existence.  This  sudden  change  in  the  status 
of  the  thing,  from  existing  "for  itself,"  from  its  position  in  the 

8  Italics  mine. 


596  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

spot  light,  will  seem  to  some  a  surrender  or  at  any  rate  a  degrada- 
tion of  its  former  existential  glory.  A  good  rationalist  will  of 
course  say  that,  on  the  contrary,  this  is  a  promotion  of  the  thing. 
It  is  thus  lifted  from  the  pit  of  existential  particularity  into  the 
glorious  light  of  universality. 

This  change  of  status  is  further  enhanced  by  the  fact  that  usually 
it  is  only  a  small  fragment  or  quality  of  the  original  thing  that  is 
used  for  this  purpose  of  getting  other  things.  And  even  this  frag- 
ment gets  a  new  incarnation  in  words  and  other  symbols  and  in  the 
nervous  system  of  beings  who  continue  to  use  it.  But  nowhere  in 
all  this  is  there  a  detached,  floating  essence.  Always  there  is  some 
remnant  of  the  old  existence,  functioning  in  a  new  and  wonderful 
way,  but  existence,  none  the  less.  Freely  conceding  that  in  reflective 
inferential  operations  specific  qualities  of  given  things  may  be  "de- 
tached" by  attention  to  serve  as  logical  data  and  as  thus  serving  may 
appropriately  be  called  "essences,"  yet,  if  we  are  good  realists, 
"critical"  or  otherwise,  we  shall  not  begin  by  converting  the  perfectly 
good  "things  and  folks"  of  immediate  experience  into  Bradley 's 
celebrated  "unearthly  ballet  of  bloodless  categories." 

A.  W.  MOORE. 
UNIVERSITY  or  CHICAGO. 


BEHAVIORISM  AND  CONSCIOUSNESS 

AS  everybody  knows,  the  quarrel  of  Behaviorism  with  introspec- 
tive psychology  is  on  no  matter  of  detail  but  goes  at  once  to 
the  fundamental  question  whether  consciousness  in  the  subjective 
sense  can  any  longer  be  made  use  of  by  science.  Introspection 
still  clings  to  consciousness  and  hence,  it  is  said,  deprives  itself 
of  the  possibility  of  scientific  accuracy  and  objective  verifiability. 
It  is  owing  to  this  that  it  has  "failed  to  yield  results  comparable  to 
those  obtained  in  kindred  sciences."1  Objective  and  accurate  and 
verifiable  results  can  be  obtained  only  by  objective  methods.  Ob- 
jectivity is  the  great  solid  advantage  of  Behaviorism,  and  through  it 
alone,  it  is  maintained,  can  a  truly  scientific  psychology  be  achieved. 
Stimulus  and  response  are  measurable  in  a  sense  that  subjective 
states  never  can  be,  hence  the  whole  hope  of  making  psychology  truly 
scientific  is  based  upon  the  success  of  the  behaviorist  method. 

That  psychology  can  never  hope  to  be  an  exact  science  in  the 
physical  or  mathematical  sense  so  long  as  it  continues  to  deal  with 
subjective  states  as  such  is  a  contention  to  which  I  think  all  must  per- 
force agree.  That  it  can  be  made  into  an  exact  science  by  the  be- 

»  Perry,  "A  Behavioristic  View  of  Purpose,"  This  JOURNAL,  XVIII,  p.  88. 


BEHAVIORISM  AND  CONSCIOUSNESS  597 

haviorist  method  is,  however,  an  entirely  different  proposition.  The 
task  of  constructing  a  psychology  in  which  consciousness  (in  the 
subjective  sense)  shall  be  entirely  omitted  and  its  place  filled  by 
various  forms  of  describable  and  measurable  and  verifiable  behavior 
is  a  much  vaster  undertaking  than  seems  generally  to  be  realized. 
Except  for  the  describability,  measurability  and  verifiability  of  its 
results,  Behaviorism  would  have  no  claim  to  greater  scientific  value 
than  introspective  psychology;  and  the  likelihood  of  our  actually 
being  able  to  measure  or  describe  in  detail  these  results  and  put  them 
into  such  uniform  sequences  as  shall  be  useful  for  science,  seems 
remote  in  the  extreme.  Professor  Watson  himself  speaks  of  one  im- 
portant type  of  behavior,  central  to  psychology,  as  being  "hidden 
from  ordinary  observation  and  more  complex  and  at  the  same  time 
more  abbreviated  so  far  as  its  parts  are  concerned  than  even  the 
bravest  of  us  could  dream. ' ' 2  And  not  only  must  this  grave  prac- 
tical obstacle  be  faced  by  those  who  would  throw  away  introspection 
and  trust  to  observation  and  measurement ;  a  more  fundamental  diffi- 
culty is  to  be  found  in  the  fact  that  the  same  psychical  process,  if 
translated  into  behaviorist  terms,  may  require  fifty  different  trans- 
lations— in  fact,  may  never  be  capable  of  being  translated  twice  alike, 
and  hence  may  never  be  again  verified  and  identified.  Professor 
Watson's  colleague,  Dr.  Lashley,  gets  a  different  tracing  every  time 
his  subject  thinks  over  a  given  sentence.  The  musculature  of  the 
larynx  and  throat  are  so  varied  that  "we  can  think  the  same  word 
by  many  different  muscular  combinations."  Suppose  now  that  we 
should  somehow  succeed  in  observing  and  measuring  the  hidden 
activities  which  are  "more  complex  and  more  abbreviated  than  even 
the  bravest  of  us  could  dream ' ' ;  how,  if  they  vary  as  Professor  Wat- 
son admits  they  do,  are  we  going  to  combine  them  into  uniformities 
that  shall  be  worth  anything  to  science  ? 

The  various  simple  reactions  and  quasi-mechanical  reflexes  can, 
of  course,  be  objectively  described  and  observed  and  put  into  se- 
quences with  their  stimuli ;  this,  in  fact,  to  some  extent,  was  done  by 
most  introspectionists  for  years  before  Behaviorism  was  heard  of. 
But  when  we  get  beyond  these  relatively  simple  processes  and  come 
to  study  those  forms  of  behavior  which  are  expected  in  the  new 
scientific  psychology  to  take  the  place  of  psychic  states,  we  are  as  a 
fact  presented  with  very  little  that  is  measurable,  describable,  veri- 
fiable or  even  observable.  One  of  the  most  serious  and  successful 
attempts  to  point  out  the  real  substitutes  for  psychic  states  is  to  be 

2  Psychology  from  the  Standpoint  of  a  Behaviorist,  p.  325. 


598  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

found  in  a  remarkable  series  of  articles  by  Professor  Perry,8  most 
of  which  appeared  in  this  JOURNAL.  The  writer  takes  up  in  detail 
a  number  of  typical  objects  of  psychological  study,  such  as  curiosity, 
docility,  purpose,  belief,  and  subjects  them  to  a  rigorous  analysis 
with  the  aim  of  putting  them  over  into  behavioristic  and  hence  ob- 
jective and  scientific  language.  No  one  can  fail  to  admire  the  sub- 
tlety and  patience  with  which  Professor  Perry  has  pursued  his  at- 
tempt, but  most  careful  readers,  I  think,  will  feel  with  me  that  the 
results  are  so  abstract,  so  lacking  in  exactness  and  verifiability,  as  to 
be  quite  useless  for  science.  Curiosity,  for  example,  is  to  mean  not 
the  psychic  state  of  wonder  but  "a  determining  tendency  [in  the 
nervous  system]  which  moves  the  organism  to  acquire  anticipatory  re- 
actions." This  is  good  so  far  as  it  goes.  But  if  the  description  is  to 
be  scientific,  surely  we  must  know  what  determining  tendency  and 
what  anticipatory  reactions  we  mean ;  we  must  be  able  to  define  and 
identify  and  observe  them  if  they  are  to  be  of  any  scientific  value. 
I  hold  in  my  hands,  for  example,  an  unopened  letter  and  wonder 
what  is  in  it.  If  our  psychology  is  to  be  scientific,  we  are  warned,  it 
must  make  no  reference  to  my  psychic  state  nor  attempt  to  use  my 
feelings  in  explaining  my  subsequent  action;  to  do  so  would  be  "to 
commit  the  fallacy  of  obscurum  per  obscurius."  *  But  I  submit 
that  the  situation  remains  no  less  obscure  if  I  am  referred  simply  to 
determining  tendencies  and  anticipatory  reactions  in  the  abstract. 
And  the  moment  we  leave  the  abstract  and  seek  to  isolate  and  identify 
these  tendencies  and  reactions  we  find  them  more  hidden,  complex 
and  abbreviated  than  the  bravest  of  us  could  dream,  and  so  variable 
and  inconstant  as  to  be  incapable  of  formulation  into  any  law  that 
will  be  concretely  significant.  Is  the  identification  and  description 
of  psychic  states  so  much  more  "obscure"  than  the  proposed  be- 
haviorist  method?  so  much  more  obscure  that  it  should  never  be 
resorted  to  as  even  a  supplement  to  "objective  observation"! 

What  would  become  of  behaviorist  description  if  psychic  states 
were  really  left  out  by  the  behaviorist  will  be  pretty  plain  to  anyone 
who  reads  carefully  Professor  Perry's  behaviorist  papers.  If  he  did 
not  revert  repeatedly  to  subjectivist,  non-behaviorist  terms,  we  should 
be  at  a  complete  loss  to  know  what  he  was  writing  about.  Various 
old  psychological  terms  are  taken  up,  stripped  of  their  subjective 

»  ' '  Docility  and  Purposiveness, ' '  Psychological  Review,  XXV,  pp.  1-20 ; 
"The  Appeal  to  Reason,"  Philosophical  Review,  XXX,  pp.  131-69;  "A  Be- 
havioristic View  of  Purpose,"  this  JOURNAL,  XVIII,  pp.  85-105;  "The  Inde- 
pendent Variability  of  Purpose  and  Belief,"  this  JOURNAL,  XVIII.  pp.  169-80; 
"The  Cognitive  Interest  and  Its  Refinements,"  this  JOURNAL,  XVIII,  pp.  365-75. 

*" Docility  and  Purposiveness,"  Psychol.  Rev.,  XXV,  p.  16. 


BEHAVIORISM  AND  CONSCIOUSNESS  599 

significance,  laboriously  worked  over  into  behaviorist  terminology, 
elaborated  with  hypothetical  sets  and  reactions,  almost  all  in  abstract 
formulation;  and  when  at  the  end  of  ten  or  a  dozen  pages  we  are 
beginning  to  wonder  whether  we  surely  are  following  the  author's 
thought,  Professor  Perry  himself  seems  to  feel  that  it  is  time  to  ex- 
plain, and  we  learn  with  some  surprise  that  the  meaning  of  the  whole 
is  that  belief  is  different  from  purpose  or  that  truth  is  not  wholly 
dependent  on  will  or  some  other  bit  of  insight  which  the  introspee- 
tionist  had  never  supposed  was  in  need  of  exposition.  I  can  imagine 
no  one  doing  this  sort  of  thing  better  than  Professor  Perry  has  done 
it,  but  I  hope  he  will  pardon  me  if  I  say  that  the  whole  process  is 
likely  to  strike  an  innocent  observer  as  a  peculiar  kind  of  tour  de 
force, — like  a  translation  of  English  into  Chinese  or  of  a  child's 
primer  into  words  of  seven  syllables — or  of  the  mountain  laboring 
and  bringing  forth  a  mouse.  I  can  not  but  wonder  whether  it  struck 
no  behaviorist  as  a  bit  odd  that  the  President  of  the  American  Philo- 
sophical Association  found  it  worth  while  to  devote  his  entire  Presi- 
dential Address  to  a  defense  of  the  view  that  reason  is  not  altogether 
negligible  in  philosophy  and  life.  I  refer  to  this  chiefly,  however,  to 
point  out  that  both  in  that  admirable  address  and  throughout  his 
behaviorist  papers,  Professor  Perry  has  to  have  recourse  repeatedly 
to  subjectivist  terms,  has  to  translate  half  a  dozen  behaviorist  pages 
into  two  lines  of  introspective  psychology,  in  order  to  clear  up  his 
meaning  even  to  his  behaviorist  colleagues. 

But  not  only  is  the  behaviorist  forced  to  make  repeated  use  of 
introspectionist  materials  in  order  to  be  intelligible;  he  also  finds 
it  necessary  to  begin  his  investigations  (if  they  are  to  be  significant) 
with  introspective  facts  and  to  keep  them  in  mind  constantly  through- 
out his  researches.  The  subjective  facts  both  set  his  problem  and 
guide  his  methods.  Take,  for  example  again,  that  ablest  of  behaviorist 
analyses,  Professor  Perry's  series  of  papers.  What  are  the  signifi- 
.cant  things  that  he  places  before  himself  and  his  readers  as  objects 
of  investigation?  Are  they  nervous  sets  and  muscular  reactions? 
No ;  they  are  docility  and  purposiveness,  belief  and  cognitive  interests. 
The  reason  for  this  is  plain.  It  is  not  physiological  responses  but 
the  various  conditions  of  consciousness  that  are  chiefly  significant  for 
him  and  for  us.  How,  moreover,  does  he  come  at  his  behaviorist  and 
physiological  conclusions?  How,  for  example,  does  he  know  that  a 
belief  is  an  anticipatory  set  or  implicit  course  of  action  correlated 
with  a  specific  object  to  which  one  has  committed  oneself  ? B  Or  that 
"it  is  the  practical  function  of  reason  to  effect  certain  internal  ad- 
justments by  which  preformed  unit-responses  are  fitted  to  a  govern- 
5  This  JOUBNAL,  XVIII,  pp.  171,  173. 


600  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ing  tendency"! *  Or  that  the  "reserved  responses"  of  most  human 
action  "must  be  conceived  to  possess  unqualified  physiological  exist- 
ence, even  though  they  are  not  in  action  and  even  though  they  should 
never  be  called  into  action "  T  T  Does  Professor  Perry  know  these 
things  because  he  or  any  one  else  has  observed  in  the  nervous  system 
or  in  the  body  the  "anticipatory  sets,"  the  "implicit"  courses  of 
action,  the  "internal  adjustments"  or  the  "connecting  channels" 
which  in  a  scientific  psychology  are  to  take  the  place  of  consciousness! 
I  am  not  denying  that  Professor  Perry's  physiological  guesses  may  be 
extremely  lucky.  The  point  is  that  his  guesses  are  based  only  in 
small  part  on  objective  observation  and  are  chiefly  arrived  at  by 
interpreting  into  terms  of  the  nervous  system  what  he  finds  in 
subjective,  conscious  life.  Thus,  so  far  is  Behaviorism  from  being 
able  to  dispense  with  consciousness  that  it  has  to  fall  back  upon  con- 
sciousness for  the  setting  of  its  problems  and  the  construction  and 
verification  of  its  hypotheses,  and  even  for  the  interpretation  of  its 
own  terminology. 

For  the  sake  of  closer  insight  into  the  behaviorist  method,  it  may 
be  worth  our  while  to  examine  at  some  length  a  typical  case  of  be- 
haviorist interpretation;  and  for  this  we  can  hardly  find  anything 
better  than  Professor  Perry's  analysis  of  purpose,  which  appeared 
in  this  JOURNAL  in  February,  1921.  Purpose,  according  to  Professor 
Perry,  has  two  well-recognized  characters :  (1)  subordination  of  means 
to  end,  and  (2)  determination  by  the  future.  Neither  of  these,  we  are 
assured,  requires  any  appeal  to  consciousness.  The  subordination 
of  means  to  end  is  to  be  interpreted  as  the  subordination  of  various 
auxiliary  activities  to  a  determining  and  persisting  tendency  or  set. 
Purpose  is  not  to  be  found  either  in  the  persisting  tendency  or  dis- 
position alone,  nor  in  the  subordinate  auxiliary  activities,  but  in  re- 
lation of  the  two.  What  now  is  this  relation  !  Plainly  it  is  not  itself 
an  activity  of  the  organism.  Nor  can  it  be  a  spatial  or  a  temporal 
relation.  The  auxiliary  activity  is  not  "subordinate"  to  the  disposi- 
tion in  the  sense  of  spatial  inclusion  nor  of  temporal  precedence  or 
sequence.  The  relation  of  subordination,  according  to  Professor 
Perry,  is  essential  to  purpose ;  but  how  is  it  going  to  be  expressed  in 
behaviorist  terms !  We  are  told  that  it  is  the  relation  between  means 
and  end ;  but  how  interpret  either  end  or  means !  It  will  not  do  to 
say  merely  that  the  auxiliary  activities  are  adapted  to  their  environ- 
ment nor  that  their  working  is  successful,8  for  this  could  be  averred 

«  This  JOURNAL,  XVIII,  p.  175. 
ilbid.,  p.  96. 

•  At  least  as  I  understand  Professor  Perry,  of.  pp.  103-04  of  his  paper  on 
"Purpose." 


BEHAVIORISM  AND  CONSCIOUSNESS  601 

of  every  reflex.  Does  then  the  on-looking  psychologist  read  purpose 
into  the  relation  and  the  activity?  If  so,  where  is  the  real  purpose? 
And  would  not  the  purpose  which  the  psychologist  reads  into  it 
either  be  a  conscious  purpose  in  the  old  bad  sense,  or  else  in  its  turn 
need  to  be  interpreted  as  the  purpose  which  some  other  on-looking 
psychologist  read  into  him,  and  so  ad  infinitumf  Thus  we  seem 
projected  upon  a  very  wild  goose  chase  indeed ;  for  of  course  we  are 
forbidden  to  interpret  the  end  or  purpose  as  a  conscious  desire  in 
the  mind  of  the  actor.  To  do  so  would  be  to  desert  Behaviorism. 

A  similar  difficulty  awaits  the  behaviorist  in  his  attempt  to  inter- 
pret the  second  of  the  well-recognized  characters  of  purpose,  namely 
"determination  by  the  future."  This  essential  characteristic  of  pur- 
pose, Professor  Perry  tells  us,  has  usually  been  explained  by  saying 
that  the  "purposive  act  is  governed  by  the  antecedently  existing  idea 
of  a  future  result."  This  simple  and  obvious  explanation,  however, 
can  not  be  accepted  by  the  behaviorist  and  must  be  refuted.  One  of 
the  chief  aims  of  Professor  Perry's  article,  in  fact,  is  to  refute  dualis- 
tic  explanations  of  human  conduct,  and  this  particular  dualistic  ex- 
planation he  refutes  in  one  short  sentence.  It  can  not  be  the  true 
explanation,  he  tells  us,  because  "it  goes  to  pieces  on  the  rock  of  dual- 
ism."9 The  simple  explanation  having  been  rejected,  we  are  pro- 
vided with  a  scientific  one.  "The  solution  would  seem  to  be  in  the 
action  of  present  dispositions  which  are  correlated  with  future  con- 
tingencies. A  calendar  of  engagements  filled  out  for  the  next  month 
exists  and  acts  in  the  present.  Nevertheless,  it  is  correlated  serially 
and  progressively  with  the  future.  Similarly,  the  responses  organ- 
ized and  serially  adjusted  so  as  to  be  executed  in  sequence  exist  now 
among  the  determining  conditions  of  present  events.  Nevertheless, 
they  are  functionally  correlated  with  a  sequence  of  events  in  the 
historical  future — in  their  own  future.  A  series  of  anticipatory  dated 
responses  is  thus  projected  upon  the  present  spatial  field  and  provides 
a  means  by  which  the  contingent  future  may  be  translated  into  the 
physically  existent  present. ' ' 10 

The  question  must  be  asked:  Is  this  "determination  by  the 
future"?  If  it  is,  then  so  is  every  reflex  a  case  of  determination  by 
the  future  and  therefore  of  purpose ;  so  is  almost  every  event  in  the 
vegetable  world  and  much  in  the  purely  mechanical  world.  Consider 
the  composition  and  potentialities  and  tendencies  of  the  seed  which 
falls  in  the  autumn,  the  decay  of  its  enclosing  shell,  the  long  lying  in 
comparative  inactivity  during  the  winter,  the  gradual  development  of 
the  germ  under  the  influence  of  vernal  sun  and  shower ;  or  the  care- 

•  P.  104. 

"P.  104. 


602  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

fully  constructed  watch  spring  and  flywheel,  so  exactly  correlated 
to  the  future  hours  and  minutes  of  coming  days.  Of  both  these  one 
could  say  as  truthfully  as  of  sets  and  tendencies  in  the  nervous  system 
that  "the  responses  organized  and  serially  adjusted  so  as  to  be  exe- 
cuted in  sequence  exist  now  among  the  determining  conditions  of 
present  events.  Nevertheless,  they  are  functionally  correlated  with  a 
sequence  of  events  in  the  historical  future — in  their  own  future." 
Possibly  the  behaviorist  will  say  that  events  and  potentialities  of 
this  sort  in  the  vegetable  and  mechanical  worlds  are  also  cases  of 
purpose  in  which  the  present  is  "determined  by  the  future."  If  so, 
what  shall  we  take  as  an  example  of  that  in  which  there  is  no  deter- 
mination by  the  future?  If  the  phrase  is  capable  of  so  wide  an  ap- 
plication as  to  include  watches  and  onions,  it  is,  of  course,  hardly 
worth  using.  Plainly,  I  should  say,  the  word  purpose  loses  all  dis- 
tinctive meaning  unless  it  be  given  its  natural  interpretation — the 
interpretation  which  every  plain  man,  every  scientist,  every  psychol- 
ogist and  every  philosopher  outside  the  behaviorist  fold  gives  it — 
namely,  that  of  a  present  desire  or  idea  of  a  future  result  determining 
to  some  extent  action  toward  that  result.  The  only  criticism  of  this 
dualistic  interpretation  of  purpose  which  Professor  Perry  gives  us  is, 
as  will  be  remembered,  that  it  "goes  to  pieces  on  the  rock  of  dualism." 
In  other  words,  dualism  is  refuted  by  being  shown  to  be  dualistic. 

This  refutation  of  a  dualistic  view  of  purpose  is  by  no  means  the 
only  instance  in  behaviorist  logic  that  looks  suspiciously  like  begging 
the  question.  To  refer  to  no  more  details,  the  general  insistence  that 
Behaviorism  should  supplant  introspection  in  the  investigation  of 
mind  on  the  ground  that  it  is  objective  and  introspection  subjective 
is  an  open  case  of  petitio.  For  the  question  at  issue  between  behavior- 
ists  and  introspectionists  is  exactly  the  question  whether  mind  is 
susceptible  of  direct  study  by  objective  methods.  To  this  question 
the  behaviorist  has  two  answers.  One  is  the  logical  and  metaphysical 
one,  which  we  shall  come  to  presently,  of  denying  the  existence  of  the 
subjective.  The  other  and  commoner  is  the  methodological  and  illog- 
ical answer  of  carefully  observing  and  writing  down — or  quite  as 
often,  imagining — various  forms  of  human  behavior  and  presenting 
the  results  as  an  objective  description  of  mind.  The  logical  nature 
of  this  procedure  will  perhaps  be  plainer  if  we  apply  it  to  an 
imaginary  discussion  in  another  field.  Two  men  are  discussing  the 
question  whether  or  not  the  value  of  a  given  individual  to  society  is 
susceptible  of  statement  in  monetary  terms.  One  of  the  disputants 
asserts  that  it  can  be  so  expressed,  the  other  denies  it.  The  former, 
thereupon,  triumphantly  produces  the  exact  figures,  in  dollars  and 
cents,  of  the  man's  income,  and  congratulates  himself  on  having 


BEHAVIORISM  AND  CONSCIOUSNESS  603 

refuted  his  opponent.  Behaviorism  can  not,  as  a  fact,  dispense  with 
the  subjective  in  its  attempts  to  describe  mind;  and  could  it  do  so, 
it  would  not  be  mind  that  it  described.  All  its  technical  equipment 
and  its  hypothetical  constructions  are  simply  irrelevant  to  the  main 
question. 

To  attack  this  main  question  in  direct  and  logical  fashion  it  is 
necessary  for  Behaviorism  to  deny  the  existence  of  consciousness  (in 
the  old-fashioned  subjective  sense),  as  some  of  the  bolder  and  more 
clear-sighted  behaviorists  have  been  consistent  enough  to  do.  Thus 
Professor  "Watson  identifies  affection  and  emotion  with  sense  processes 
or  "pattern  reactions,"  particularly  in  the  glands  and  viscera;11 
while  thought  is  to  be  interpreted  as  the  activity  of  the  language 
mechanisms.12  In  similar  fashion  Dr.  Frost  defines  awareness  as  "the 
relation  between  two  neural  arcs"; 13  and  Professor  Bawden  defines 
perception  as  "an  attitude  toward  the  object  perceived,  a  reverbera- 
tion within  the  sensorium. ' ' "  For  Professor  Holt,  volition  is  a 
generating  proposition  or  logico-mathematical  entity  descriptive  of 
the  motions  of  a  living  body.15  There  is,  to  be  sure,  a  good  deal 
of  hedging  on  the  part  of  nearly  all  behaviorists  on  the  question  of 
the  denial  of  consciousness.  Sometimes,  it  is  true,  they  deny  it  only 
from  the  methodological  point  of  view.  But  with  equal  certainty  (if 
they  mean  what  they  say)  at-  times  they  deny  it  absolutely,  that  is, 
they  deny  its  existence  as  a  subjective  entity.  "It  is  a  serious  mis- 
understanding of  the  behaviorist  position, ' '  writes  Professor  Watson, 
"to  say,  'Of  course  a  behaviorist  does  not  deny  that  mental  states 
exist;  he  merely  prefers  to  ignore  them.'  He  ignores  them  in  the 
same  sense  that  chemistry  ignores  alchemy  and  astronomy  horo- 
scopy. "  16  "  Thought  is  not  different  in  essence  from  tennis  playing, 
swimming,  or  any  other  activity  except  that  it  is  hidden  from  ordi- 
nary observation  and  is  more  complex."17  "Consciousness  is  not 
something  inferred  from  behavior,"  Professor  Singer  wrote  at  the 
very  dawn  of  the  behaviorist  movement ;  "it  is  behavior."  18  "What 
we  observe  in  so-called  introspection,"  according  to  Professor  Bawden, 

11  "Image  and  Affection  in  Behavior,"  this  JOURNAL,  X,  pp.  421-28,  and 
Psychology,  Chap.  VI. 

12  "Image  and  Affective  Behavior,"  Psychology,  Chap.  IX:  "Is  Thinking 
Merely  the  Action  of  Language  Mechanisms,"  Brit.  Jour,  of  Psy.,  XI,  pp.  87- 
104. 

is  "Cannot  Psychology  Dispense  with  Consciousness?"  Psychol.  Bev.,  XXI, 
pp.  204-211. 

i* " Presuppositions  of  a  Behaviorist,"  Psychol.  Bev.,  XXV,  pp.  171-190. 

IB  The  Concept  of  Consciousness,  Chap.  XIV. 

ie  Brit.  Jour,  of  Psy.,  XI,  p.  94. 

IT  Psychology,  p.  325. 

is  "Mind  as  an  Observable  Object,"  this  JOURNAL,  VIII,  p.  180. 


604  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

"is  usually  but  the  inner  bodily  beginnings,  hidden  from  our  view, 
of  the  same  behavior  which  in  its  overt  manifestations  is  described 
by  external  observation."19 

This  absolute  denial  of  consciousness  to  mind  is  in  fact  a  necessity 
for  Behaviorism.  For  if  consciousness  be  admitted  as  a  genuine 
characteristic  of  mind,  Behaviorism,  which  leaves  it  out  of  account, 
cannot  be  the  science  of  mind.  And  if  consciousness  be  efficient  as 
well  as  real,  Behaviorism  cannot  be  a  science  at  all — not  even  of  beha- 
vior. In  so  far,  therefore,  as  Behaviorism  admits  the  reality  of  con- 
sciousness, but  claims  to  be  a  real  science  of  behavior,  it  takes  up  the 
position  of  that  form  of  Materialism  which  depicts  consciousness  as  an 
inefficient  epiphenomenon.  This,  I  think,  is  quite  undeniable ;  for  the 
moment  you  admit  that  consciousness  has  the  least  imaginable  in- 
fluence upon  our  motor  activities,  those  activities  cease  to  be  explicable 
by  physiological  conditions  plus  stimulus;  there  is  a  lacuna  in  the 
series  of  physical  explanation;  the  behaviorist 's  description  fails  to 
reach  the  whole  relevant  event,  and  such  partial  description  as  he 
gives  can  never  be  generalized.  If  consciousness  has  any  efficiency, 
I  repeat,  Behaviorism  cannot  be  even  a  science  of  behavior.  It  is,  of 
course,  the  realization  of  this  fact  that  has  led  the  bolder  members  of 
the  school  into  the  actual  denial  of  the  existence  of  consciousness 
in  any  other  sense  than  as  another  name  for  behavior ;  and  obviously 
to  assert  that  consciousness  is  nothing  but  behavior  is  merely  a  some- 
what shy  and  apologetic  way  of  denying  its  existence,  in  the  usual 
sense,  altogether.  But,  if  the  behaviorist  who  admits  the  existence  of 
consciousness  is  forced  to  take  up  the  position  of  one  branch  of  Materi- 
alism, the  behaviorist  who  denies  its  existence  altogether  plainly  adopts 
the  position  of  the  other  branch.  The  difficulties  of  this  school  of 
Materialism  have  long  been  obvious.  In  fact,  I  think  it  would  be 
safe  to  say  that  every  one,  including  the  behaviorists  themselves, 
knows  that  the  denial  of  the  existence  of  consciousness  (in  the  old 
and  subjective  sense)  is  really  absurd.  The  question  needs  no  argu- 
ment— and  in  fact  is  hardly  arguable.  The  recognition  of  the  reality 
of  consciousness  coupled  with  the  denial  of  its  efficiency  is,  however, 
hardly  less  absurd.  It  demands  an  amount  of  credulity  which  very 
nearly  passes  understanding.  Yet  unless  one  or  the  other  of  these 
positions  can  be  made  tenable,  Behaviorism  falls  even  as  a  scientific 
method.  As  a  supplement  to  introspection  it  may  be  useful  enough ; 
but  once  the  behaviorist  uses,  it  independently  or  takes  it  as  a  science, 
he  is  inevitably  committed — no  matter  how  little  he  may  like  it — to  a 
materialistic  metaphysic  with  all  its  crudities. 

JAMES  BISSETT  PRATT. 
WILLIAMS  COLLIGB. 

l.  Bev.,  XXV,  p.  179. 


KNOWLEDGE  OF  OTHER  MINDS  605 

KNOWLEDGE  OF  OTHER  MINDS 

EFORE  we  consider  how  it  is  that  we  know  other  minds  we 
-•— '  must  state  what  we  mean  by  mind.  We  shall  not  attempt 
any  exhaustive  analysis  of  the  nature  of  mind  but  simply  endeavor 
to  point  out  some  distinguishing  feature  by  which  mind  may  be 
recognized  as  an  object  of  knowledge.  Excuse  the  dogmatic  tone  for 
the  sake  of  brevity. 

I 

Mind  has  two  aspects  that  should  be  clearly  distinguished.  In 
one  aspect  mind  is  that  which  is  undergoing  sensuous  experience. 
In  the  other  aspect  mind  is  knowledge  of  experience  other  than 
that  which  it  is  now  undergoing.  Mind  is  not  only  conscious  of 
current  experience  but  also  of  experience  which  occurred  under  other 
spatial  and  causal  conditions;  also  of  experience  which  other  minds 
have  undergone.  Hence  knowledge  of  experience  is  a  very  different 
thing  from  the  process  of  experience  which  the  mind  may  undergo  in 
a  given  time,  place  and  causal  situation.  To  experience,  and  to  know 
the  meaning  of  experience,  which  is  knowledge,  are  two  quite  distinct 
things.  Mind  is  that  which  knows  the  meaning  of  experience. 
The  meaning  of  a  given  experience  is  that  total  unit  of  experience 
of  which  the  given  experience  is  a  fragment. 

It  is  possible  to  experience  an  object  without  knowledge  of  the 
object.  This  occurs  when  one  hears  a  sound  in  the  dark  without 
knowing  what  it  means,  or  sees  a  glint  of  light  in  the  distance  with- 
out understanding  its  significance  or  undergoes  a  stream  of  sensu- 
ous experience  without  interpreting  it  or  retaining  it  in  mind  be- 
cause of  preoccupation  with  other  matters.  It  is  also  possible  to 
have  knowledge  of  an  object  without  experience  of  it,  as  when  one 
is  told  what  another  mind  has  experienced,  or  when  one  infers  the 
existence  and  character  of  an  object  which  no  one  has  ever  ex- 
perienced. Even  in  case  of  those  objects  which  we  say  we  have 
experienced,  our  knowledge  ordinarily  runs  far  beyond  our  ex- 
perience, whether  past  or  present.  When  I  look  at  a  chair,  for 
instance,  I  say  that  I  experience  the  chair.  But  what  I  actually 
experience  is  only  a  very  few  of  those  elements  that  go  to  make  up 
the  chair,  namely,  that  color  which  belongs  to  the  chair  under 
these  particular  conditions  of  light,  that  shape  which  the  chair 
displays  when  viewed  from  this  angle,  etc.  I  am  able  to  know 
the  chair  only  because  my  mind  can  supplement  this  immediate 
experience  with  the  experience  which  was  undergone  in  many 
other  situations  vastly  different  from  the  present  one  with  respect 
to  time,  place  and  causal  conditions.  Also,  in  most  cases,  my 


»,<)<;  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

knowledge  of  the  chair  is  further  supplemented  by  knowledge 
gained  from  other  minds,  based  upon  orders  of  experience  which 
have  never  befallen  me. 

So  we  must  distinguish  between:  (1)  experience  as  a  process 
taking  place  at  a  certain  time,  within  the  bounds  of  a  certain  place 
and  under  certain  causal  conditions,  one  of  which  is  a  sensitive 
organism;  and  (2)  experience  as  that  which  is  known  to  have  oc- 
curred, or  known  to  be  about  to  occur,  or  known  to  be  that  which 
would  occur  if  certain  temporal,  spatial  and  causal  conditions  were 
provided.  We  shall  ordinarily  use  the  word  experience  to  desig- 
nate number  (1),  while  knowledge  will  indicate  number  (2).  The 
process  of  experience  is  limited  to  a  certain  time  and  place  and  to 
certain  causal  conditions;  knowledge  of  that  process  is  not  limited 
to  any  particular  time  or  place  or  causal  conditions.  Knowledge 
surmounts  time,  place  and  cause.  Knowledge  is  the  gathering  up 
of  experience  into  a  region  where  the  thief  of  time  does  not  steal 
and  where  the  moth  and  rust  of  place  and  cause  do  not  corrupt. 
The  unique  characteristic  of  mind,  which  we  wish  to  make  plain, 
is  precisely  this:  Mind  is  knowledge  and  hence  is  not  limited  by 
time,  nor  place  nor  cause. 

Many  objections  might  be  raised  to  the  statement  that  knowl- 
edge is  super-spatial,  super-temporal  and  super-causal.  But  we 
believe  that  all  these  objections  arise  from  one  or  other  of  two 
misunderstandings.  There  is  first  the  misunderstanding  that  arises 
from  confusing  experience  and  knowledge;  second,  there  is  the 
misunderstanding  that  arises  from  confusing  knowledge  with 
error.  Let  us  take  up  these  misunderstandings  in  order. 

Experience  and  knowledge  are  confused  because  of  the  ambigu- 
ous character  of  consciousness.  Consciousness  is  partly  process 
of  experience  and  partly  knowledge.  For  the  extrovert  conscious- 
ness is  chiefly  experience;  for  the  introvert  it  is  chiefly  knowledge, 
but  it  is  always  both  to  some  degree.  Because  of  this  fact,  who- 
ever identifies  mind  with  consciousness  will  confuse  knowledge  and 
experience.  Consciousness,  in  so  far  as  it  consists  of  experience, 
is  shaped  by  time,  place  and  cause.  In  so  far  as  it  consists  of 
knowledge  it  is  independent  of  time,  place  and  cause.  But  mind, 
as  knowledge,  is  much  more  than  consciousness.  I  know  much 
more  than  that  of  which  I  am  immediately  conscious  at  this  mo- 
ment. Whatever  may  be  one's  theories  of  subconsciousness,  knowl- 
edge is  a  word  which  refers  to  much  else  besides  that  which  is  at 
the  focus  of  consciousness.  Mind  is  that  which  includes  all  that 
a  man  knows.  Mind  as  knowledge  is  not  subject  to  the  temporal, 
spatial  and  causal  conditions  of  consciousness. 


KNOWLEDGE  OF  OTHER  MINDS  607 

The  second  misunderstanding  arose  from  confusing  knowledge 
and  error.  Knowledge  is  truth.  Erroneous  knowledge  is  not 
knowledge  at  all.  Error  is  subject  to  time,  place  and  cause.  Truth 
is  not.  Truth  is  that  portion  of  reality  which  is  known.  Truth  is 
not  affected  by  time,  place  or  cause;  but  there  are  three  things 
which  appear  to  be  changes  of  truth.  These  three  are:  (1)  true 
knowledge  may  cease  and  error  take  its  place;  (2)  error  may  cease 
and  knowledge  take  its  place;  (3)  further  knowledge  may  be  added 
to  that  already  known.  In  none  of  these  cases  is  knowledge  changed 
although  lack  of  clear  distinctions  may  lead  one  to  think  so.  When 
knowledge  ceases  and  error  takes  its  place  we  have  a  diminution 
of  mind,  for  mind  is  knowledge  and  where  knowledge  is  not  mind 
is  not.  It  is  true  that  we  say  a  mind  is  in  error.  But  mind  in 
error  is  mind  not  by  virtue  of  the  error,  but  by  virtue  of  whatso- 
ever approximation  to  truth  that  mind  may  have;  for  mind  may 
be  more  or  less  fully  mind.  Error  itself  is  a  word  that  refers  to 
that  which  more  or  less  remotely  approximates  truth.  It  is  that 
which  aims  at  truth.  Mind  is  identical  with  that  which  knows. 
To  know  is  to  be  identical  with  truth  and  truth  transcends,  by 
comprehending,  time,  place  and  cause.  Hence  mind  is  super- 
temporal,  spatial  and  causal. 

In  case  of  error  changed  to  truth,  we  have  something  which 
does  not  apply  to  our  present  position  because  error  is  not  knowl- 
edge. Error  is  subject  to  time,  place  and  cause  and  generally  is 
error  precisely  because  of  that  fact.  But  error  is  not  knowledge, 
hence  the  case  is  beside  the  point. 

In  case  of  adding  further  truth  to  that  already  known  there  is 
no  change  of  true  knowledge.  We  have  further  knowledge  added 
but  no  change  in  that  already  possessed.  I  may  know  a  chair  to 
have  a  certain  color.  When  the  character  of  the  light  is  changed 
it  reveals  another  color.  My  original  knowledge  is  not  changed. 
It  is  still  true  that  under  the  conditions  of  light  first  prevailing, 
the  chair  bore  a  certain  color  and  that  truth  can  never  be  changed. 
Throughout  all  time  it  will  be  true  that  the  chair  in  that  particular 
situation  bore  that  particular  color. 

So  we  conclude  that  mind,  in  so  far  as  it  consists  of  knowledge, 
has  a  timeless,  spaceless,  causeless  mode  of  existence.  Minds  are 
associated  with  three  levels  of  existence  which  may  be  called  the 
physical,  the  organic  and  the  rational.  The  process  of  experience 
appears  at  the  organic  level;  but  knowledge  does  not  appear  until 
we  reach  the  rational  level.  Rationality  is  the  ability  to  survey  the 
experiences  of  other  times  and  places  and  causal  conditions  than 
those  in  which  the  organism  is  now  placed ;  the  ability  to  survey  the 


608  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

experience  undergone  by  other  organisms;  and  finally  the  ability 
to  reduce  all  these  experiences  to  a  single  unity  and  know  them  all 
as  one  total  object.  This  is  knowledge.  It  is  only  at  this  level  that 
mind  is  completely  developed.  Organisms  experience,  but  they  do 
not  know.  The  physical  and  the  organic  are  the  foundations  on 
which  mind  is  builded,  rather  than  mind  itself. 

To  know  other  mind  is  to  know  not  only  a  physical  object,  and 
not  only  an  organism  that  experiences,  but  preeminently  it  means 
to  know  that  which  reasons,  i.e.,  that  which  surveys  and  unifies  the 
experiences  of  different  times,  places  and  causal  conditions  into  one 
timeless,  placeless  object  of  knowledge. 

We  do  not  pretend  to  have  made  an  exhaustive  statement  of  the 
nature  of  mind.  We  have  simply  stated  those  features  of  mind 
which  it  is  necessary  to  have  before  us  in  order  to  deal  with  our 
real  problem,  which  is  how  we  know  other  minds. 

II 

The  knowledge  of  an  object,  whether  that  object  be  a  stick  or  a 
mind,  is  not  immediately  impressed  upon  the  mind.  An  object  is  a 
certain  order  of  experience;  but  one  can  never  know  an  object  if 
he  knows  nothing  save  the  immediate  experience.  He  must  be  able 
to  know  the  order  of  experience  in  its  totality,  which  means  that 
he  must  know  not  only  those  elements  which  are  now  being  experi- 
enced but  also  those  which  have  been  experienced  and  those  which 
will  be  experienced  in  the  future.  To  know  the  object  which  he  is 
experiencing  he  must  know  what  is  that  total  unit  of  experience  of 
which  the  immediate  experience  is  but  one  small  fraction.  This 
total  unit  of  experience  is  what  we  shall  call  the  meaning  of  the  im- 
mediate experience.  To  know  a  stick  is  to  know  the  meaning  of  an 
immediate  experience.  To  know  another  mind  is  also  to  know  the 
meaning  of  an  immediate  experience. 

Suppose  I  experience  a  strip  of  brownness  against  the  side  of 
yonder  hill.  What  is  the  meaning  of  this  brownness?  Perhaps  I 
say,  at  first,  that  it  is  a  shadow  on  the  ground.  I  then  say  that  I 
have  knowledge  of  a  shadow.  But  I  discover  that  I  am  mistaken. 
I  next  conclude  that  it  is  a  discoloration  of  the  soil  at  that  point. 
Then  I  opine  it  is  a  snake.  No,  it  is  some  dried  leaves.  Finally  I 
ascertain  it  is  a  stick.  This  I  do  by  the  simple  process  of  putting 
myself  in  those  situations  in  which  I  shall  have  other  experiences 
related  to  the  original  experience  in  such  manner  as  to  reveal  to  me 
what  would  be  that  total  order  of  experience  which  would  ensue  if 
I  placed  myself  in  all  conventional  situations  relative  to  the  original 
brownness.  That  order  of  experience  is  the  stick. 


KNOWLEDGE  OF  OTHER  MINDS  609 

But  the  immediate  experience  which  means  stick  may  also  mean 
tree  in  so  far  as  it  is  the  fragment  of  a  tree.  It  may  also  mean 
hurricane  if  it  has  been  cast  to  the  ground  from  a  tree  top  by  a 
hurricane.  It  may  also  mean  fire  and  warmth  if  it  can  be  used  to 
kindle  a  fire.  But  most  significant  of  all,  it  can  also  mean  other 
mind.  Let  us  illustrate  this. 

As  I  observe  the  stick  I  may  note  that  it  moves  back  and  forth. 
It  is  the  wind,  I  think,  which  causes  it  to  sway.  But  suddenly  to 
my  surprise  I  may  discover  that  the  movements  of  the  stick  de- 
scribe the  signals  of  a  code  with  which  I  am  familiar.  The  stick 
is  signaling  a  message  to  me  which  I  understand.  It  is  signaling 
the  question :  Do  you  know  me  ?  I  am  now  sure  that  the  stick 
means  not  only  stick  but  also  other  mind.  I  approach  and  find  that 
the  stick  projects  above  an  embankment.  I  come  nearer  still  and 
find  that,  lying  behind  the  embankment,  and  holding  one  end  of 
the  stick,  is  my  friend  who  laughs  up  at  me  and  enjoys  my  surprise. 

I  say  I  see  my  friend  beneath  the  embankment.  But  what  do 
I  experience?  I  actually  experience  certain  sensuous  qualities  in 
a  certain  situation  which  have  a  dual  meaning,  just  as  the  brownish- 
ness  had  a  dual  meaning.  The  brownishness  meant  stick  and  also 
other  mind.  These  new  sensuous  qualities  mean  human  organism 
and  also  other  mind.  Human  organism  is  not  necessarily  mind  any 
more  than  stick.  If  mind  had  expressed  itself  to  me  through  certain 
kinds  of  sticks  as  commonly  as  it  had  expressed  itself  to  me  through 
human  organism,  I  would  recognize  mind  in  the  stick  quite  as 
readily  as  in  the  flesh.  To  be  sure  there  are  many  reasons  why 
human  organism  is  better  adapted  to  express  mind  than  a  stick. 
It  is  highly  probable  that  our  instincts  are  so  adapted  to  the  hu^ 
man  organism  that  we  are  much  more  attentive  to  it  than  we  can 
naturally  be  to  sticks.  Also  the  human  organism,  by  reason  of  its 
capacity  for  vocalization  and  gesticulation  of  all  sorts,  is  better 
adapted  to  the  making  of  symbolic  signs.  But  the  principle  still 
holds  that  human  organism  is  not  the  criterion  of  other  mind. 
Neither  do  we  know  other  mind  by  reasoning  on  the  analogy  that 
since  I  am  a  human  organism  and  also  mind,  that  other  human 
organism  is  likewise  a  mind.  Neither  do  we  know  other  mind  by  an 
instinct  which  recognizes  a  human  organism  as  the  embodiment  of 
mind.  There  are,  of  course,  instincts  that  cause  human  organisms 
to  associate  with  one  another.  But  association  of  human  organisms 
does  not  necessarily  involve  mutual  knowledge  of  minds. 

It  is  symbolism  that  reveals  other  mind.  The  reason  symbolism 
reveals  other  mind  is  because  it  reveals  knowledge  which  is  inde- 
pendent of  the  time,  space  and  cause  of  the  immediate  situation; 


610  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

and  mind  is  precisely  knowledge  that  is  independent  of  the  time, 
space  and  cause  of  the  immediate  situation.  Symbolism  surmounts 
time  and  space  because  it  introduces  into  the  immediate  situation 
meanings  which  can  not  become  objects  of  immediate  experience 
except  in  situations  which  are  far  removed  in  time  and  place  and 
cause  from  the  immediate  situation.  Symbolism  introduces  us  to 
a  timeless,  spaceless,  causeless  state  of  existence,  or  nullifies  time, 
space  and  cause,  by  flooding  the  immediate  situation  with  foreign 
meanings.  When  a  symbolic  object  floods  the  present  situation  with 
foreign  meanings  it  expresses  that  which  transcends  the  present 
situation.  That  which  transcends  the  temporal,  spatial,  causal  con- 
ditions of  the  present  situation  is  precisely  mind.  In  so  far  as  any 
object,  through  symbolism,  reveals  knowledge  of  that  which  is  inac- 
cessible to  immediate  experience,  it  reveals  mind,  because  mind  is 
knowledge  of  that  which  is  inaccessible  to  immediate  experience. 

We  said  that  the  stick  might  mean  tree,  fire  and  hurricane  as 
well  as  stick;  and  yet  no  other  mind  was  involved.  But  in  that 
case  the  stick  symbolized  the  meanings  of  my  own  mind.  The  stick 
was  simply  the  symbol  by  which  I  kept  in  consciousness,  or  brought 
to  consciousness,  that  which  I  myself  knew.  Of  course  the  stick 
might  be  a  means  by  which  I  discovered  further  knowledge  which 
I  had  not  theretofore  possessed,  but  in  that  case  the  stick  would 
not  be  a  symbol  at  all  and  we  are  now  considering  the  stick  only 
as  a  symbol.  The  symbolism  of  the  stick  always  expresses  mind, 
although  it  may  be  my  own  mind  which  it  expresses.  How  one  dis- 
tinguishes between  his  own  mind  and  that  of  others  we  shall  con- 
sider at  once. 

That  portion  of  all  possible  experience  which  each  mind 
undergoes  is  different  from  that  of  any  other  mind.  Differences  in 
constitution  of  the  organism,  differences  in  the  sense  organs,  dif- 
ferences in  the  time,  location  and  causal  conditions  in  which  the 
organism  is  placed  when  the  experience  is  undergone,  all  conspire 
to  render  the  process  of  experience,  which  each  mind  undergoes, 
distinctly  different  from  that  of  every  other  mind.  Hence  that 
knowledge  which  constitutes  my  mind  is  different  from  that  which 
constitutes  another  mind.  When  I  am  introduced  to  knowledge,  a 
timeless,  spaceless  totality,  which  is  different  from  that  which  con- 
stitutes my  own  mind,  I  am  aware  of  other  mind.  No  objects  are 
more  readily  distinguished  from  cne  another  than  minds  because 
none  are  so  different  from  one  another.  The  complex  diversities 
of  those  total  systems  of  experience  that  make  up  minds  are  more 
different  from  one  another  than  those  fragments  of  experience 
which  constitute  non-mental  objects.  We  know  other  minds  in  the 


BOOK  REVIEWS  611 

same  fashion  that  we  know  our  own  and  we  know  our  own,  oft- 
times,  no  better  than  we  know  other  minds.  The  symbolism  which 
floods  the  present  situation  with  foreign  meanings  brings  to  our 
consciousness  a  mind.  This  mind  may  be  either  our  own  or  an- 
other. Which  it  be  is  readily  discerned. 

Minds  are  constantly  undergoing  both  mutual  assimilation  to 
one  another  and  also  diversification  from  one  another.  They  as- 
similate one  another  in  so  far  as  they,  by  means  of  symbolism,  com- 
municate to  one  another  that  timeless,  spaceless  knowledge  of  ex- 
perience which  constitutes  each.  Thus  minds  comprehend  one  an- 
other. But  they  constantly  diversify  in  so  far  as  the  process  of 
experience  which  each  undergoes  is  different. 

So  we  conclude  that  to  know  other  mind  is  to  know  a  total  order 
of  experience  which,  as  process  of  experience,  underwent  time, 
space  and  cause,  but  which,  as  knowledge,  exists  in  a  timeless, 
spaceless,  causeless  unity.  Such  a  unified  totality,  transcending 
time  and  space,  can  make  itself  known  as  such  to  other  mind  by 
means  of  symbolism.  Symbolism  serves  to  flood  the  immediate 
situation  with  meanings  which  can  be  objects  of  immediate  experi- 
ence only  at  remotely  distant  times  and  places  and  under  other 
causal  conditions.  Hence  symbolism  in  a  sense  surmounts  time, 
space  and  cause  and  reveals  that  knowledge  transcending  time, 
space  and  cause  which  is  mind. 

HENRY  NELSON  WIEMAN. 

OCCIDENTAL  COLLEGE,  Los  ANGELES. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Eastern  and  Western  Cultures  and  their  Philosophies.    LIANG  SHU- 
MING.    Shanghai.    1922.1 

Those  who  are  familiar  with  contemporary  China  know  that 
there  recently  has  happened  something  known  as  the  "New  Cul- 
ture Movement."  To  those  who  fear  nothing  but  change  and  those 
who,  as  Bertrand  Russell  said,  take  "moralization  for  philosophy," 
this  movement  is  thought  to  mean  the  complete  destruction  of  the 
ancient  Chinese  culture,  and  therefore  is  too  radical.  But,  in  fact, 
it  means  an  evolution  rather  than  a  revolution  of  the  Chinese  cul- 
ture. The  "new"  culture  movement  may  be,  after  all,  simply  the 
self -consciousness  and  self-examination  of  the  old.  Mr.  Liang's 
book  is  the  first  conscious  and  serious  attempt  to  grasp  the  central 

i  The  page  numbers  referred  to  in  the  following  are  based  on  a  copy  of 
the  preliminary  Peking  edition.  There  is  no  English  translation. 


612  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

idea  and  to  show  the  excellences  and  the  defects  of  the  old  Chinese 
culture  in  comparison  with  the  European  and  the  Indian. 

William  James  said  that  every  great  philosopher  has  his  own 
vision,  and  that  if  one  gets  that,  one  can  easily  understand  his 
system.  This  is  Mr.  Liang's  method  in  treating  the  different  types 
of  the  world  culture.  To  Mr.  Liang  the  fountain  of  life  is  the  ever 
struggling  and  never  ceasing  Will.  All  peoples  have  this  Will  but 
every  people  has  its  own  direction  to  lead  it  to.  There  are  three 
possible  directions: 

1.  To  struggle  to  get  what  we  want;  to  try  to  change  the  en- 
vironment in  order  to  satisfy  our  desires. 

2.  Not  positively  to  solve  the  different  problems  of  life,  but  to 
find  satisfaction  in  the  given  situation ;  not  to  realize  but  to  harmon- 
ize our  desires. 

3.  Not  to  solve  the  problems,  nor  to  leave  them  unsolved,  but  to 
try  to  get  rid  of  the  desires  that  cause  them. 

Proceeding  along  these  three  different  directions  and  using  these 
different  methods,  the  European,  the  Chinese,  and  the  Indian 
peoples  work  out  independently  their  respective  cultures,  which, 
according  to  Mr.  Liang,  are  but  moods  of  life.  Thus  the  funda- 
mental spirit  of  the  European  culture  is  the  realization  of  desires; 
that  of  the  Chinese  is  the  harmonization  of  desires;  that  of  the 
Indian  is  the  negation  of  desires  (pp.  62-72). 

Since  the  European  mood  of  life  is  to  struggle  forward,  the  Euro- 
pean culture  is  characterized  by  ability  in  controlling  nature,  the 
scientific  method,  and  democracy  in  the  sense  that  each  and  every 
individual  claims  his  own  right  to  oppose  authority.  These  are  its 
excellences.  With  them  side  by  side  come  its  defects.  There  is  too 
much  intellect,  calculation,  and  self-assertion  along  with  selfishness. 
The  individual  stands  in  the  centre  of  the  universe  and  treats  every- 
thing outside  of  him  as  either  material  or  rivals.  Means  is  for  the 
end ;  present  for  the  future.  There  is  too  much  to  do,  but  too  little 
to  en  joy  (p.  232). 

The  Chinese  mood  of  life,  of  which  Mr.  Liang  chose  Confucianism 
as  the  representative,  is  just  the  opposite.  Its  fundamental  idea  is 
to  repudiate  calculation  and  intellect.  It  teaches  not  doing  for 
something,  but  "doing  for  nothing."  Following  natural  feeling, 
or  what  Mr.  Liang  called  intuition,  a  mother  loves  her  baby,  and 
a  baby  loves  its  mother.  This  love  is  not  means  for  the  future, 
but  the  end  in  and  for  itself  (pp.  174-176). 

Confucius  also  said:  "I  have  no  course  for  which  I  am  prede- 
termined and  no  course  against  which  I  am  predetermined."  This 
means  that  one  must  not  make  any  foregone  conclusion  and  not 


BOOK  REVIEWS  613 

insist  on  one  reasoning.  If  one  holds  one  reasoning  and  does  not 
admit  change,  one  has  to  push  to  the  extreme  and  thus  miss  the  mean. 
For  instance,  if  one  adhere  to  the  doctrine  of  universal  love,  like 
Jesus,  one  has  to  love  one's  enemies  and,  like  Buddha,  to  refrain  from 
killing  any  animal.  Furthermore,  one  must  not  destroy  anything  in 
this  world;  there  is  no  reason  to  stop  midway.  But,  according  to 
Confucianism,  since  by  nature  one  loves  one's  parents  more  and 
others'  less,  so  ought  one  to.  The  degree  of  one's  love  of  different 
people  ought  to  be  different,  because  towards  others  in  one's  intuition 
there  is  a  different  intensity  of  love.  To  Confucius,  it  is  wrong  to 
insist  beforehand  on  any  objective,  changeless  doctrine,  but  right  to 
follow  one's  natural  feeling  and  let  it  go  (pp.  160-161).  These 
aspects  of  Confucianism  are  included  in  the  conception  of  Jen  (this 
Chinese  word  is  often  translated  ''benevolence"  but  is  more  than 
that) .  Jen  means  the  sensitiveness  of  the  natural  feeling  or  intuition 
and  the  pursuit  of  it  without  calculation  of  the  consequence  or 
reasoning  about  a  general  rule.  Thus  life  is  not  dependent  upon 
what  is  without,  but  upon  itself.  So  there  can  be  neither  gain  nor 
loss.  There  is  always  joy,  but  never  sorrow. 

As  the  European  people  have  too  much  calculation,  the  Indian 
have  too  much  insistence.  The  Indian  people  want  to  get  rid  of  the 
problems  of  life,  because  they  want  to  seek  a  fundamental  solution 
of  them.  They  want  to  solve  problems  that  are  unsolvable.  Life 
itself  is  a  flux,  but  they  worry  about  its  uncertainty  and  change. 
They  are  too  sensitive  to  the  affairs  of  life,  so  they  fall  back  to 
the  complete  negation  of  it  (p.  135).  So  the  Indian  mood  of  life, 
of  which  Mr.  Liang  chooses  Buddhism  as  representative,  is  to  try  to 
return  to  the  state  of  pure  sensation  or  pure  experience.  According 
to  Mr.  Liang,  in  pure  experience  there  is  no  change  and  distinction. 
In  pure  experience  every  impression  of  a  flying  bird  is  a  motionless 
image.  It  is  our  feeling  that  connects  these  successive  images  together 
and  puts  them  in  motion.  In  pure  experience  there  is  no  distinction 
between  object  and  subject.  It  is  our  intellect  that  makes  this  sharp 
demarcation  and  antithesis.  If  we  return  to  the  state  of  pure  expe- 
rience, we  shall  have  knowledge  of  nothing.  There  is  real  eternity, 
since  there  is  no  change.  There  is  real  One,  since  there  is  no  distinc- 
tion. This  is  Absolute.  This  is  Wisdom  (pp.  108-112.) 

These  are  the  salient  points  of  the  three  types  of  the  world's 
culture  as  Mr.  Liang  sees  them.  Mr.  Liang  advises  the  Chinese 
people  to  accept  completely  European  sciences  and  to  resume  critically 
the  Confucianistic  attitude  towards  life.  He  also  sees  that  the 
European's  life  of  calculation  is  near  its  end  and  that  the  "Western 
people  are  bound  to  change  their  way  and  to  follow  Confucius.  But 


614  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

that  is  not  all.  There  must  be  a  time  when  mankind  will  become  very 
sensitive  to  the  unsolvable  problems  of  life  such  as  death,  old  age  and 
sickness;  they  will  then  begin  to  appreciate  the  Indian  culture  and 
to  adopt  it.  In  fact,  the  three  cultures,  according  to  Mr.  Liang, 
represent  the  three  successive  stages  of  human  development  (pp.  259- 
263).  But  since  science,  as  Mr.  Liang  points  out,  is  an  organic  part 
of  the  Western  individualistic  and  utilitarian  mood  of  life,  how  can 
it  be  combined  organically  with  Mr.  Liang's  Confucianism?  Science 
for  science's  sake;  we  may  invent  science  for  nothing;  but  it  is 
through  and  through  a  product  of  pure  intellect.  A  life  of  feeling 
and  intuition  is  for  art,  not  for  science.  I  see  quite  clearly  that 
Confucianism  is  possible  for  science,  but  not  the  Confucianism  of 
Mr.  Liang's  interpretation.  Mr.  Liang's  Confucianism  presupposes 
too  much  the  pre-existing  harmony  of  man's  feeling  and  the  goodness 
of  man 's  nature. 

Mr.  Liang  considers  Bertrand  Russell's  appeal  to  man's  instinct 
of  creation  as  an  indication  of  the  fact  that  the  Western  peoples  are 
going  to  assume  the  attitude  of  "doing  for  nothing."  I  may  also 
say  that  Professor  Hobhouse's  "rational  good"  and  Professor 
Dewey's  "good  of  activity"  are  no  less  strong  indications.  Still  I 
do  not  quite  see  why  the  Western  peoples  should  adopt  Confucianism 
completely  and  why  future  mankind  should  all  be  followers  of 
Buddha.  It  seems  that  Mr.  Liang,  being  always  a  student  of  Buddh- 
ism, has  too  strong  a  monistic  preconception  that  leads  him  to  suppose 
that  the  three  existing  types  of  culture  have  exhausted  all  the  possible 
ways  of  life  and  that  mankind  is  bound  to  take  or  reject  one  or  the 
other  as  they  are. 

Since  Mr.  Liang's  book  is  dealing  with  so  comprehensive  a  subject 
matter  and  his  prediction  of  the  fate  of  the  cultures  is  so  far  in  the 
future,  it  is  unnatural  to  expect  that  every  one  should  agree  with 
him.  It  seems  to  me  that  his  interpretations  of  Buddhism  and  Con- 
fucianism are  of  interest  and  value,  no  matter  whether  Buddhism 
and  Confucianism  are  really  as  he  says  or  not.  I  think  nobody  can 
read  these  two  parts  of  his  book  without  being  impressed  by  his 
originality  and  conscientiousness.  Mr.  Liang  certainly  has  his  vision. 
This  is  enough  for  a  philosophical  work  to  justify  its  existence. 

YU-LAN  FUNO. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

JOURNAL  OP  EXPERIMENTAL  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  V,  No.  5.  Octo- 
ber, 1922.  Influence  of  Vision  in  Acquiring  Skill :  H.  A.  Carr  and 
E.  B.  Osb&urn.  Differences  in  the  Oral  Responses  to  Words  of  Gen- 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  615 

eral  and  of  Local  Significance :  V.  R.  McClatchy.  The  Cardio-Pneu- 
mo-Psychogram  and  its  Use  in  the  Study  of  the  Emotions :  J.  A.  Lar- 
son. A  Study  in  Grades  and  Grading  under  a  Military  System :  R. 
L.  Bates.  Studies  in  Dissociation :  L.  E.  Travis.  The  Selectiveness 
of  the  Eye 's  Response  to  Wave-Length  and  its  Change  with  Change 
of  Intensity :  7.  A.  Haupt. 

GREGORIANUM.  Vol.  Ill,  No.  3.  September,  1922.  Anglia  quae- 
rens  fidem,  II :  L.  J.  Walker.  Determinazioni  idealiste — Metafisica : 
G.  Mattiussi.  Salva  illorum  substantia,  I:  H.  Lennerz.  Novation 
et  la  doctrine  de  la  Trinite  a  Rome  au  milieu  du  troisieme  siecle,  I : 
A.  D'Ales. 

JOURNAL~OF  INTERNATIONAL  ETHICS.  Vol.  XXXIII,  No.  1.  Octo- 
ber, 1922.  The  Hindu  Dharma:  S.  Radhakrishnan.  The  Commen- 
surability  of  Values:  R.  K.  Pemberton.  The  Genesis  of  the  Moral 
Judgment  in  Plato:  Rupert  C.  Lodge.  Sanctioning  International 
Peace :  C.  F.  Taeusch.  The  Relation  of  Ethics  to  Social  Science :  0. 
F.  Boucke.  Hamlet :  C.  C.  H.  Williamson.. 

Pillsbury,  W.  B.:  The  Fundamentals  of  Psychology.  Revised 
edition.  New  York :  Macmillan  Company.  1922.  xiv  +  589  pp. 

Warren,  Howard  C.:  Elements  of  Human  Psychology.  Boston: 
Houghton  Mifflin  Company.  1922.  416  pp.  $2.25. 

Dunlap,  Knight:  Elements  of  Scientific  Psychology.    St.  Louis: 

C.  V.  Mosby  Company.    1922.    368  pp.    $3.50. 

Givler,  Robert  C. :  Psychology.  The  Science  of  Human  Behavior. 
New  York :  Harper  Brothers.  1922.  382  pp.  $3.00. 

Moore,  G.  E. :  Philosophical  Studies.  New  York :  Harcourt,  Brace 
&  Company,  Inc.  1922.  viii  +  342  pp. 

Moore,  G.  E. :  Principia  Ethica.  Reprinted.  New  York:  Mac- 
millan Company.  1922.  xxvi  +  232  pp. 

Rignano  Eugenio :  Come  Funziona  la  Nostra  Intelligenza.  Bolog- 
na :  Nicola  Zanichelli.  1922.  46  pp. 

de  Wulf,  Maurice:  Mediaeval  Philosophy.  Illustrated  from  the 
System  of  Thomas  Aquinas.  Harvard  University  Press.  1922. 
151  pp. 

Hollingworth,  H.  L. :  Judging  Human  Character.     New  York: 

D.  Appleton  &  Company.    1922.    xiii  +  268  pp.    $2.00. 
Micklem,  E.  R. :  Miracles  and  the  New  Psychology.    A  Study  of 

the  Healing  Miracles  of  the  New  Testament.  New  York:  Oxford 
University  Press,  American  Branch.  1922.  142  pp.  $2.50. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS 

The  Annual  Meeting  of  the  American  Psychological  Association 
will  take  place  at  Cambridge,  Mass.,  December  27,  28  and  29.  The 
sessions  will  be  held  in  Emerson  Hall,  Harvard  University. 


616  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Papers  of  general  and  theoretical  import  will  be  placed  in  the 
sessions  on  Wednesday,  December  27.  The  business  meeting  will  be 
Wednesday  evening.  The  sessions  of  Thursday  will  include  a  sympo- 
sium arranged  by  Section  I  of  the  A.  A.  A.  S.  and  the  address  of 
Professor  Bott,  the  retiring  vice-president  of  Section  I.  The  annual 
dinner  of  the  Association  followed  by  the  Presidential  address  and 
smoker  will  be  Thursday  evening.  Friday  will  be  devoted  to  sessions 
of  the  Section  of  Clinical  Psychology.  In  the  afternoon,  the  session 
will  be  at  the  Boston  Psychopathic  Hospital. 

Abstracts,  not  exceeding  400  words  and  written  in  triplicate  must 
be  in  the  hands  of  Professor  Edwin  Boring,  Emerson  Hall,  Cam- 
bridge, Mass.,  by  November  8th. 

A  joint  meeting  of  the  Eastern  and  Western  Divisions  of  the 
American  Philosophical  Association  will  be  held  at  Union  Theological 
Seminary,  New  York  City,  December  27,  28  and  29.  Professor  John 
Dewey  will  deliver  the  Paul  Carus  Lectures  on  the  attempt  to  apply 
a  theory  of  experience  to  certain  metaphysical  problems. 

The  afternoon  sessions  will  be  largely  devoted  to  the  lectures  by 
Professor  Dewey,  and  the  morning  sessions  to  the  reading  and  discus- 
sion of  papers  offered  by  members.  On  Wednesday  and  Thursday 
evenings  respectively,  the  smoker  and  annual  dinner  will  be  held,  and 
at  these  times  also  addresses  by  the  presidents  will  be  delivered. 

Abstracts  of  papers  should  be  in  the  hands  of  Professor  G.  A. 
Tawney,  University  of  Cincinnati,  Cincinnati,  Ohio,  not  later  than 
November  10th.  The  papers  offered  should  be  limited  to  twenty 
minutes  in  reading. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  23  NOVEMBER  9,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  GROUNDS  OF  PRESUMPTION * 

THE  note  of  pure  skepticism,  not  mistakable  for  denial,  has 
always  been  more  distinct  in  English  and  in  Scotch  philoso- 
phy than  it  ever  was  in  German  philosophy  either  before  or  after 
Kant,  or  in  French  philosophy  before  or  after  Comte.  In  Hume 
it  became  dominant,  and  not  for  the  last  time.  In  Balfour,  in  1879, 
it  became  the  theme  of  the  composition. 

A  Defense  of  Philosophic  Doubt  never  had  the  vogue  it  de- 
served, or  the  consideration  which,  for  the  clarification  of  the  hu- 
man mind,  it  should  have  received.  It  got  a  bad  name  at  the  start, 
as  an  attack  on  inductive  science,  in  particular  on  evolution,  which 
it  was  not ;  and  as  an  apology,  which  it  was  not,  for  the  Thirty-nine 
Articles.  For  the  first  of  these  misapprehensions,  incompetent  re- 
viewing and  inattentive  reading  were  to  blame.  For  the  second, 
the  author  himself  was  to  blame  because,  inadvertently  or  unwisely, 
he  used  throughout  the  words  ''belief"  and  "faith,"  colorful  with 
religious  connotation,  when  he  should  have  adhered  to  the  white- 
light  philosophical  terms,  "assumption,"  "certitude"  and  "pre- 
sumption. ' ' 

In  part,  however,  the  disappointing  influence  of  the  book  is  at- 
tributable to  the  circumstance  that  it  soon  went  out  of  print,  and 
for  forty  years  was  almost  unobtainable.  Meanwhile,  the  tide  of 
ideas  ran  swift,  if  not  always  deep,  and  threw  up  a  resounding 
surf.  It  required  moral  courage  to  reissue  the  Defense  without 
other  revision  than  trifling  verbal  alterations  and  a  few  notes,  made 
a  long  while  ago.  This  was,  however,  the  right  thing  to  do.  It 
saved  a  significant  bench  mark  from  obliteration. 

Lord  Balfour's  major  thesis  is  that  not  only  all  speculative  phi- 
losophy but  also  all  inductive  science,  observational  or  experi- 
mental, and  all  historical  inference,  rest  upon  assumptions  that 
are  unproved  and  unprovable.  These  assumptions  he  calls  "ulti- 

iA  Defence  of  Philosophic  Doubt:  Being  an  Essay  on  the  Foundations 
of  Belief.  By  Arthur  James  Balfour,  F.  R.  S.  Member  of  the  Institute  of 
France:  Honorary  Fellow  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge.  A  new  edition.  Lon- 
don, Hodder  and  Stoughton,  Ltd.  1921.  Pages  x  +  355. 

617 


618  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

mate  beliefs"  and  "grounds  of  belief,"  using  the  two  expressions 
interchangeably.  He  identifies  them  with  "self-evident  proposi- 
tions" (page  4)  and  tells  us  in  italics  that  among  the  "full  'dif- 
ferentia' of  ultimate  beliefs"  is  the  fact  that  "we  require  no 
grounds  for  believing  them  at  all"  (page  7).  Grounds  of  belief 
are  always  to  be  discriminated  from  the  causes,  or  antecedents,  of 
belief.  "The  enquiry  into  the  first  is  psychological,  the  enquiry 
into  the  second  is  philosophical"  (page  5).  "It  is  strictly  impos- 
sible that  any  solution  of  the  question  'how  come  I  to  believe  this' 
should  completely  satisfy  the  demand  'why  ought  I  to  believe  it' ' 
(page  6).  "The  business  of  philosophy  is  to  deal  with  the  grounds, 
not  the  causes,  of  belief"  (page  5),  but  not,  of  course,  to  attempt 
to  prove  them  (page  8).  However,  "if  philosophy  is  neither  to 
investigate  the  causes  nor  to  prove  the  grounds  of  belief,  what  .  .  . 
is  it  to  do?"  Its  business,  as  Lord  Balfour  apprehends  it  "is  to 
disengage"  the  grounds  of  belief,  "to  distinguish  them  from  what 
simulates  to  be  ultimate,  and  to  exhibit  them  in  systematic  order." 

Demonstration  of  this  thesis  is  undertaken  through  a  searching 
and  extraordinarily  acute  examination  of  empirical  logic  as  set 
forth  by  Mill;  of  the  theory  of  historical  inference;  of  Kantian 
transcendentalism  as  restated  by  Caird ;  of  the  argument  from  gen- 
eral consent,  the  argument  from  success  in  practise  and  the  argu- 
ment from  common  sense;  of  psychological  idealism  (Berkeley); 
of  the  test  of  inconceivability  (Spencer) ;  and  of  Mr.  Spencer's 
proof  of  realism.  Not  many  conscientious  readers  have  survived 
these  pages  with  unscathed  doubt  that  all  systems  of  thought,  em- 
pirical no  less  than  a  priori,  are  built  upon  unproved  and  improv- 
able assumptions. 

But  tangled  up  with  Lord  Balfour 's  major  thesis  are  minor 
theses,  each  of  which  has  crept  in  as  pure  assumption.  One  of  them 
he  obviously  believes,  and  would  defend.  Whether  he  believes  any 
of  the  others  I  am  not  sure.  I  am  not  even  sure  that  he  meant  to 
present  them.  I  am  sure  only  that  he  has  neither  proved  nor  elim- 
inated them. 

Most  obtrusive  of  these  unproven  but  not  eliminated  theses  is 
the  assumption  that  in  self-evident  propositions  we  find  certitude. 
The  inattentive  reader  probably  carries  away  an  impression  that 
Lord  Balfour  holds  this  assumption  to  be  true,  but  I  find  no  incon- 
testable evidence  that  he  does.  Somewhat  less  obtrusive  is  the  as- 
sumption, which  Lord  Balfour  unquestionably  does  believe,  that 
the  grounds  of  belief  are  themselves  beliefs.  Least  obtrusive,  but 
neither  insignificant  nor  unimportant,  is  the  assumption  that  the 
grounds  of  belief  are  equivalent  to  reality,  or  may  be  identified 
with  it. 


THE  GROUNDS  OF  PRESUMPTION  619 

It  is  precisely  upon  the  issues  presented  by  these  assumptions, 
or  minor  theses,  that  philosophy  has  been  engaged  throughout  the 
years  since  the  Defense  was  written.  The  product  of  criticism  and 
restatement  is  not  inconsiderable.  We  have  a  new  general  philoso- 
phy of  relativism,  and  three  particular  varieties  of  it,  namely,  a 
new  logic,  a  new  pragmatism,  and  a  new  realism.  Over  against 
these  we  have  a  new  absolutism. 

The  new  relativism  has  conditioned  our  self-evident  truths.  It 
denies  that  things  which  are  equal  to  the  same  thing  are  necessarily 
equal  to  each  other  eternally,  or  that  parallel  straight  lines  are 
necessarily  parallel  to  infinity. 

Lord  Balfour  will,  of  course,  object  that  if  these  denials  are 
empirical  they  are  invalid.  Einstein  and  the  astronomers  could 
not  perturb  him.  But  the  new  relativism  is  not  bounded  by  em- 
piricism. It  compels  us  to  ask,  and,  if  we  can,  to  answer  the  ques- 
tion, "To  what  intelligence  is  a  self-evident  proposition  equiva- 
lent to  certitude?"  The  only  answer  we  can  make  is,  "To  an 
infallible  intelligence,"  and  human  intelligence  is  not  infallible. 
So  there  we  are.  Our  grounds  of  belief,  our  ultimate  assumptions, 
are  not  certainties.  They  are  presumptions  only. 

Moreover,  they  are  not  beliefs.  The  grounds  of  presumption 
are  no  more  beliefs  than  the  grounds  of  the  validity  of  a  contract 
are  beliefs.  The  grounds  of  the  validity  of  a  contract  are  the  con- 
ditions attached.  If  these  are  present  and  fulfilled  the  contract 
holds;  otherwise  it  does  not.  The  grounds  of  presumption  are  the 
conditions  present  and  attaching  to  assumption.  They  are  the  ad- 
jectives, not  the  substantives  of  assumption.  They  only  can  con- 
vert assumption  into  presumption. 

There  are  four  imperative  conditions  of  presumption,  and  three 
of  them  are  adjective  factors  of  self-evident  belief.  There  is  no 
discovery  here,  unless,  possibly,  to  minds,  if  there  are  such,  un- 
aware that  the  self-evident  can  be  factorized,  and  that  no  one  fac- 
tor is  adequate.  Each  of  the  four  conditions  at  one  or  another  time 
has  been  isolated  by  one  or  another  philosopher  as  a  test  or  criter- 
ion of  ultimate  truth.  Lord  Balfour  has  not  overlooked  or  ignored 
any.  Seriatim  he  has  mercilessly  scrutinized  each  and,  in  its  isola- 
tion, discredited  it.  But  he  has  not  seen,  at  least  he  has  given  us 
no  occasion  to  suspect  that  he  has  seen,  that  any  one  of  the  four 
enters  as  an  adjective  factor  into  the  self-evident. 

To  name  the  adjective  factors  of  the  self-evident  is  presumably 
enough  to  obtain  recognition  of  the  subsistent  relation  affirmed. 
No  one  whose  attention  has  been  called  to  it  is  likely  to  deny  it. 
They  are,  then,  the  insistent,  the  persistent  and  the  consistent. 


620  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Nobody  calls  a  proposition  self-evident  unless  it  forces  itself 
upon  consciousness  uninvited.  It  is  intuitive.  Nobody  calls  a 
proposition  self-evident  unless,  as  Spencer,  with  unnecessary  ur- 
gency, contended,  it  persists  in  consciousness  in  spite  of  efforts  to 
evict  it.  And  nobody  calls  two  or  more  propositions  self-evident 
if  they  contradict  one  another. 

How,  then,  can  we  say  that  the  self-evident  is  unconditional! 
And  if  we  admit  that  it  is  conditional  do  we  not  admit  both  that 
the  self-evident  can  be  factorized  and  that  its  factors  are  the  grounds 
of  its  presumptive  truth?  If  so,  Lord  Balfour,  in  saying  both  that 
the  grounds  of  belief  are  self-evident  propositions,  and  that  we  re- 
quire no  grounds  at  all  for  believing  them,  has  fallen  into  the  lan- 
guage of  contradiction. 

The  fourth  condition  of  presumption  is  best  approached  through 
further  observations.  The  new  logic  has  not  been  content  with 
sharpening  the  edges  of  categorical  discrimniation  and  following 
the  lure  of  quantification  until  logic  and  mathematics  have  been 
exposed  as  one  identity  masquerading  as  two  demons.  It  has  ex- 
plored the  realms  of  causation  as  intrepidly  as  Mill  did  and  has 
made  a  better  triangulation  than  his.  The  old  base  lines,  "ante- 
cedent," "consequent,"  and  "condition,"  have  been  abandoned, 
and  the  once  outstanding  peaks,  "a  cause"  and  "the  cause"  ap- 
pear with  diminished  altitude.  Each  is  seen  now  as  one  factor  only 
of  a  situation,  and  "the"  is  held  to  mean  only  relative  size,  or 
other  importance.  A  situation  conceptually  factorized,  conceived 
in  terms  of  its  factors,  a  wood  thought  of  as  trees,  is  thereby  logic- 
ally resolved,  the  new  logic  says,  into  its  causes.  The  factors  con- 
ceived as  integrated,  the  trees  thought  of  as  a  wood,  are  thereby 
converted  logically,  the  new  logic  avers,  into  their  effect.  Actual 
(phenomenal)  causation  is  a  kinetic  process  of  integration.  The 
cause  of  a  dynamic  situation  is  the  kinetic  integration  of  its  static 
and  kinetic  factors,* 

Moreover,  the  distinction  here  made  between  causation  logical 
and  causation  phenomenal  is  conceptual  only.  It  has  no  dynamic 
existence,  a  fact  so  nearly  "ultimate"  that  Lord  Balfour  might 
have  been  expected  to  take  notice  of  it.  He  has  not  adequately  done 
so.  His  contention  that  philosophy  has  to  do  with  the  grounds  of 
belief  only,  and  not  with  the  causes  of  belief  he  has  thrown  into  re- 
lief by  ignoring  the  question  whether  or  in  what  way  causes  and 
grounds  are  related. 

As  now  conceived,  causes  and  effects  are  not  only  equivalent, 
(they  have  always  been  held  to  be  that)  and  all  causes  are  or  have 

2Cf.  the  chapter  on  "Order  and  Possibility"  in  Oiddings'  Studio  in  the 
Theory  of  Human  Society,  1922. 


THE  GROUNDS  OF  PRESUMPTION       621 

been  caused  (this  also,  with  reservations  as  to  a  First  Cause,  has 
always  been  held)  but  also,  effects  are  not  terminal  points.  Now, 
this  last  assumption,  oddly,  has  not  always  been  held,  at  least  not 
always  held  in  mind.  Certain  states  of  mind,  and  self-evident 
truths  preeminently,  if  not  actually  thought  of  as  akin  to  nirvana, 
have  been  dealt  with  in  philosophical  discussion  as  if  they  were. 
Yet  logically  they  are  not,  as,  certainly,  they  are  not  dynamically. 
All  states  of  mind,  including  contemplation,  are  reaction  states,  and 
all,  including  contemplation,  react  both  logically  and  dynamically. 
Insistence,  persistence  and  consistence,  therefore,  the  grounds  of 
presumption,  resolve  into  causation.  However,  the  grounds  of  as- 
sumption (or  belief)  and  the  causes  of  assumption  (or  belief)  are 
not  identical  throughout  the  whole  extent  of  causation.  Not  all 
causes  of  assumption  are  grounds  of  assumption ;  morons  unhappily 
(and  notoriously)  make  assumptions;  but  all  true  grounds  of  as- 
sumption are  causes  of  assumption. 

We  here  arrive  at  the  new  (or,  should  we  say,  at  the  newest) 
pragmatism.  The  grounds  of  assumption  do  things.  They  cause  or 
participate  in  causing  presumption.  Presumptions,  in  turn,  cause, 
or  participate  in  causing  further  assumptions,  conclusions,  beliefs, 
what  you  will.  Pragmatism  has  seized  upon  this  aspect  of  assump- 
tion. It  has  taken  doing,  working,  productiveness  as  its  ground  of 
belief. 

Carefully  defined,  productiveness  is  a  ground  (one  ground)  of 
presumption,  but  the  careful  definition  is  imperative,  and  the  limita- 
tion to  one  plot  of  ground  in  four  is  not  removable  by  logical  con- 
veyance. Insistence,  persistence  and  consistence  can  neither  be 
conveyed  nor  eliminated,  nor,  if  they  seem  not  to  bear  fruits  of 
esthetic  or  moral  value,  be  condemned  as  unproductive  (as  the 
withered  fig  tree  was),  unless  we  are  prepared  to  say  that  it  makes 
no  difference  whether  the  product  of  presumption  is  truth,  error 
or  obfuscation.  If  what  we  demand  is  truth  and  more  of  it,  the 
product  of  presumption  must  be  a  body  of  truths  that  hold  together. 
Presumptions  must  work  as  working  hypotheses  that  work  out.  In 
a  word,  the  product  of  presumption  must  be  not  values,  which  Wil- 
liam James,  unhappily,  and  too  many  of  his  earlier  disciples  were 
never  able  to  eliminate,  but  philosophy  and  science.  The  whole 
matter  has  been  put  as  clearly  and  tersely  as  it  probably  ever  will 
be,  by  Lord  Haldane,  who  says,  ' '  The  gap  in  the  foundations  of  the 
old  beliefs  has  been  largely  the  result  of  reflection,  and  it  is  not  by 
the  stimulation  of  emotion,  but  only  in  further  reflection,  that  there 
can  be  hope  of  filling  it  up. ' ' 3 

s  The  Eeign  of  Relativity,  page  4. 


622  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

All  this  means  that  assumptions  which,  being  causes,  as  they 
necessarily  are,  of  further  assumption,  are  acceptable  as  presump- 
tions only  if  the  new  truths  which  they  yield  us  are,  like  our  older 
presumptions,  persistent  and  consistent  and  resolvable  into  truths 
that  are  insistent.  It  means  further,  that  each  new  crop  of  philo- 
sophical and  scientific  products  indefinitely  must  so  qualify,  and 
that  all  of  them  must  be  consistent  with  the  old  ones.  And  this  is 
to  say  that  they  must  be  projective.  They  must  be  points  of  a  curve, 
the  equation  of  which  is  constant.  They  must  be  components  of  a 
body  of  coherent  truths,  insistent,  persistent  and  consistent, 
throughout  the  whole  extent  of  experience,  past  and  future. 

Accordingly,  the  fourth  ground  of  presumption  is  projection, 
which  may  be  defined  as  consistent  philosophical  working  through- 
out the  range  of  experience,  past  and  future.  As  working  hypothe- 
ses presumptions  must  turn  out  to  be  convertible  into  both  new 
abstracts  and  new  concretes:  new  conceptions  and  new  perceptions. 
This  brings  us  to  the  new  realism. 

The  old  realism  was  a  bootless  attempt  to  eliminate  concreteness 
from  reality  and  to  identify  reality  with  abstraction  or  the  abstract. 
Its  merit  was  that  it  was  an  attempt  to  arrive  at  consistency.  Is 
color  real  ?  No,  Lord  Balf our  says,  following  the  older  notions,  be- 
cause it  is  only  a  sensation  produced  by  the  vibrations  of  material 
particles  and  "the  smallest  trial  is  sufficient  to  convince  us  that 
to  represent  in  imagination  uncolored  vibrating  atoms  is  a  task  al- 
together beyond  our  powers"  (page  249).  Is  a  lump  of  ice  real? 
No,  because  it  melts  into  water.  Is  water  real?  No,  because  it  be- 
comes a  cloud  of  steam.  Is  the  cloud  of  steam  real  ?  No,  because  it 
disappears  in  invisible  vapor.  So,  by  negation  of  the  negation  ad 
infinitum  reality  became  the  non-phenomenal.  Thence,  facilis  des- 
census,  it  became  the  absolute,  the  unknowable. 

But  step  by  step  with  this  evolution  grew  relativism,  and  rela- 
tivism became  katabolic.  Without  pretending  that  we  could  get 
rid  of  the  unknowable,  we  balked  at  the  absolute,  and  turned  im- 
patiently from  nirvana.  Without  asking  ourselves  why,  or  on  what 
grounds,  we  first  refused  to  think  of  reality  as  the  statically  per- 
sistent, and  then  permitted  ourselves  to  think  of  it  as  the  persis- 
tently kinetic,  the  kinetically  persistent,  the  ceaselessly  carrying 
on  and  producing.  Then  neo-realism,  actual  and  unabashed,  set 
about  self-justification. 

Assuming  that  the  old  realism  had  tried  most,  if  not  all,  of  the 
possible  ways  of  going  wrong,  and  that  the  error  of  each  lay  in  ex- 
clusion or  denial,  the  new  realism  turned  to  inclusiveness.  It  af- 
firmed that  the  concrete  is  real,  no  less  than  the  abstract.  The  ice 


THE  GROUNDS  OF  PRESUMPTION  623 

is  real,  but  as  ice  it  is  not  total  reality.  The  water  and  the  steam 
are  real,  but  neither  is  complete  reality.  Nor  would  an  infinity  of 
equivalent  modes,  forms,  or  manifestations  be  the  whole  of  reality. 
There  is  also  the  relation  of  one  form  or  mode  to  another,  through- 
out the  series,  and  the  relation  of  this  relation  to  the  totality  of  rela- 
tions, and  these  relations  also  are  real.  Or,  to  put  it  all  now  in 
other  terms,  reality  is  total  experience  and  more.  It  includes  past 
and  future,  actual  and  possible  experience  and  more.  That,  at 
least,  is  how  we  have  to  think  about  it,  because  we  have  been 
driven  to  assume  that  all  experience  is  real,  in  some  sense  or  way, 
but  that  we  do  not  know,  and  may  not  presume,  that  human  ex- 
perience exhausts  reality. 

It  follows  that  conceptions  (abstractions)  are  convertible  into 
concretes  (perceptions)  and  that  these,  in  turn,  are  convertible 
into  new  conceptions,  and  so  on  indefinitely.  Reality,  therefore, 
to  summarize  all  this  in  a  formula,  is  not  merely  a  (a  concrete)  or 
merely  p  (an  abstraction),  or  merely  x  (an  unknown)  :  it  is  x(a  p), 
and  x(a  p}  must  be  convertible  into  x(b  q)  or  into  y(a  p)  or  into 
y(b  q). 

So,  at  last,  we  are  brought  through  these  developments  of  rela- 
tivism to  a  corrected  view  of  the  nature,  functions  and  relations 
of  philosophy,  logic  and  science.  Distinctions  are  clarified. 

Philosophy  is  concerned  with  the  grounds  of  presumption,  and 
with  ultimate  presumptions.  Its  business  is  to  bring  our  assump- 
tions, beliefs  and  faiths  face  to  face,  and  let  those  survive  that  can. 
The  survivors  we  may  not  accept  as  certainties,  but  we  may  accept 
them  as  presumptions.  The  strength  of  presumption  increases  as 
the  death-rate  of  beliefs  rises. 

While  philosophy  may  not  confound  itself  with  religious  faiths 
or  with  esthetic  or  moral  values,  nor  lose  itself  in  them,  it  should 
not  ignore  them  nor  let  them  alone.  All  of  them  build  upon  pre- 
sumptions. These  presumptions  philosophy  should  scrutinize,  and 
pronounce  them  philosophically  valid  or  invalid,  as  impartially  as 
it  judges  the  presumptions  underlying  inductive  science.  The 
grounds  of  judgment  are  the  grounds  of  presumption  which  have 
been  considered. 

The  business  of  logic  is  to  scrutinize  conceptions,  and  bring 
about  consistency  among  them.  The  business  of  science  is  to  bring 
about  consistency  between  conceptions  and  perceptions,  between 
inference  (or  deduction)  and  observation. 

The  new  absolutism  that  has  developed  in  the  face  of  the  new 
relativism  has  not  been  so  much  a  product  of  philosophy,  as  here 
defined,  as  of  mathematics.  The  new  mathematicians  are  adventur- 


624  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ing  where  philosophers  now  hesitate  to  tread.     I  have  commented 
upon  their  venture  in  an  earlier  volume  of  this  JOURNAL.* 

FRANKLIN  H.  GIDDINGS. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVZBSITY. 


MEMORY:   A  TRIPHASE  OBJECTIVE  ACTION 

DEPLORABLE  it  is  that  the  commendable  enterprise  of  at- 
tempting to  study  the  facts  of  psychology  in  an  objective 
manner  has  not  developed  without  regrettable  aspects.  To  mention 
only  one  of  the  unfortunate  conditions,  why  should  it  be  necessary, 
in  order  to  be  objective,  to  reduce  complex  human  behavior  to  ex- 
tremely simple  processes  ?  Such  a  reduction  we  find  in  the  descrip- 
tion of  memory  as  simple  habit  actions.  Accordingly,  we  attempt 
in  the  following  paper  to  make  an  objective  analysis  of  memorial 
behavior  without  transforming  such  activity  into  simple  processes 
easily  described  but  not  actually  constituting  a  part  of  human  be- 
havior equipment. 

I.    THE  NATURE  OP  MEMORY  REACTIONS 

Memory  reactions  constitute  those  delayed  or  postponed  re- 
sponses to  stimuli  in  which  (1)  the  adjustment  stimulus  is  no 
longer  present  when  the  response  is  made  and  consequently  must 
be  substituted  for;  that  is  to  say,  a  substitute  stimulus-object  or 
condition  must  serve  to  call  out  the  delayed  reaction  or  response 
phase  of  the  memory  behavior,  or  (2)  the  stimulus  object  itself 
must  again  be  available  after  some  absence.  In  the  latter  case,  al- 
though the  absence  may  be  an  exceedingly  brief  one,  we  must  still 
look  upon  the  effective  stimulus-object  as  a  substitute  for  the  ad- 
justment stimulus  which  in  this  instance  may  be  the  same  object  but 
in  a  different  temporal  setting. 

More  definitely  may  we  characterize  memory  reactions  by  re- 
ferring to  them  as  suspended  or  continuous  reactions.  Probably 
the  latter  description  is  much  more  to  the  point.  The  fundamental 
characteristic  of  true  memory  reactions  is  that  they  start  at  some 
period  of  time,  pass  through  another  time  interval  which  is  a  less 
active  or  suspended  stage,  and  are  finally  brought  to  completion  in 
a  third  and  active  stage.  Or  when  this  last  part  of  the  reaction 
does  not  occur  we  have  the  opposite  fact,  namely,  forgetting.  The 
main  emphasis  in  all  cases,  however,  is  on  the  fact  of  temporal  con- 

«"The  Method  of  Absolute  Posit,"  this  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIV,  No.  1,  Jan- 
uary 4,  1917. 


MEMORY:  A  TRIPE  AS  E  OBJECTIVE  ACTION      625 

tinuity,  although  there  is  a  period  of  indiscernible  action  in  between 
the  two  more  active  phases.  The  emphasis  on  the  continuity  of 
memory  reactions  is  made,  first,  because  there  is  a  period  of  ap- 
parent non-action  before  the  final  phase  of  the  memory  act  is  ex- 
ecuted, and  secondly,  because  we  are  dealing  with  the  actual  be- 
havior of  a  person  covering  a  period  of  time.  Consequently  the 
phases  or  partial  acts  might  erroneously  be  considered  as  being 
independent  discontinuous  activities.  That  a  memory  behavior  seg- 
ment is  a  single  continuous  action  no  matter  how  long  a  time  is 
required  for  its  transpiration  is  clear  when  we  agree  that  memory 
reaction  begins  at  the  moment  we  make  an  engagement  with  some- 
one to  meet  him  at  a  definite  time  and  to  end  when  we  actually  do 
meet  him  at  the  appointed  time  and  place.  That  is  to  say,  the 
memory  action  goes  on  from  one  period  to  the  other. 

We  find  it  exceedingly  helpful  if  we  study  memory  reactions 
as  the  concrete  actual  responses  of  persons.  For  one  thing, 
it  enables  us  to  see  how  it  is  possible  for  a  person,  who, 
although  he  does  other  things  at  the  same  time  that  he  makes  an 
engagement,  and  also  while  keeping  it  as  well  as  in  between  these 
two  points  of  time,  is  no  less  continuing  the  identical  memory  ac- 
tivity throughout  the  whole  series  of  -time  periods.  Is  not  the 
situation  very  like  the  case  of  a  person  who  is  going  somewhere 
but  who  in  the  same  time  interval  can  greet  a  friend  on  the  way? 
The  hypothesis  of  the  temporal  continuity  of  memory  action  is 
rather  strengthened  than  weakened  by  the  analogy  between  these 
otherwise  very  different  sorts  of  behavior  when  the  person  can 
actually  stop  to  chat  with  his  friend. 

While  we  naturally  choose  for  illustrative  purposes  types  of 
memorial  behavior  which  lend  themselves  advantageously  to  the 
presentation  of  our  conception,  we  still  insist  that  the  case  of  mem- 
ory stands  no  differently  when  we  consider  informational  reactions 
rather  than  grosser  sorts  of  behavior.  Here  we  must  be  more  care- 
ful, however,  to  avoid  mere  language  habits  or  informational  learn- 
ing, which  are  quite  different  sorts  of  phenomena  from  memory  ac- 
tion, as  we  will  presently  point  out. 

A  memory  reaction,  it  follows  then,  can  not  be  studied  and 
understood  unless  we  consider  the  action  from  the  standpoint  of 
all  of  the  time  periods  involved.  Of  these  time  periods  we  may  ob- 
serve the  distinct  existence  of  three,  namely,  (1)  the  inceptive,  (2) 
the  between  stage,  and  (3)  the  cousummatory  stage.  To  these  three 
time  units  there  correspond  three  phases  of  a  unit  action,  to  wit, 
(1)  the  projection  or  initiatory  phase,  (2)  the  middle  phase,  and 
(3)  the  recollective  or  consummately  phase.  The  middle  phase,  be- 


626  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

cause  of  its  relative  invisibility  and  submerged  operation  we  may 
practically  neglect  although  it  is  a  genuine  phase  of  all  memorial 
behavior.  In  general  descriptions  of  memory  we  disregard  the 
middle  phase  although  it  is  presupposed  in  both  the  projection  and 
recollective  phases.  Accordingly,  the  brief  examination  of  each  of 
the  two  end  phases  will  in  our  opinion  not  only  reveal  evidence  that 
a  memorial  behavior  segment  requires  for  its  operation  a  definite 
time  interval,  be  it  minutes  or  months,  but  also  that  memory  con- 
sists of  a  single  triphase  continuous  action. 

Whenever  we  start  a  memory  reaction  it  is  invariably  implied 
that  the  behavior  initiated  shall  be  continued  or  suspended  until 
some  specified  posterior  time.  The  immediate  act  is  initiated  in 
order  that  some  related  action  should  occur.  We  make  engage- 
ments in  order  to  keep  them;  we  memorize  in  order  to  recite  after 
some  longer  or  shorter  intervening  time  interval. 

Furthermore,  the  intervening  phase  of  action  which  superficially 
appears  as  no  action  whatever  must  in  fact  be  looked  upon  as 
a  positive  mode  of  psychological  adaptation,  since  the  memorial  be- 
havior necessitates  this  interval  between  the  initiation  of  the  action 
and  its  final  consummation.  A  moment's  reflection  regarding  the 
inhibition  of  reaction  is  a  convincing  argument  of  the  positive 
actual  character  of  the  suspended  phase  of  memorial  behavior,  and 
here  the  consummatory  phase  of  the  action  is  only  temporarily  in- 
hibited or  postponed.  After  signing  the  contract  the  waiting  of 
ninety  days  to  pay  the  amount  nominated  in  the  bond  is  very  much 
a  part  of  the  total  memory  action  involved. 

When  the  final  or  completion  phase  of  a  memory  behavior  seg- 
ment operates,  its  mode  of  action  is  conditioned  by  and  implies  the 
functioning  of  the  middle  phase.  The  final  action  must  occur  only 
after  a  suitable  given  period  which  is  conditioned  by  the  stimulat- 
ing circumstances  of  the  entire  action.  Not  only  are  the  two  termi- 
nal actions  incomplete  and  insignificant  unless  they  are  inextri- 
cably intercorrelated,  but  they  must  also  be  in  the  same  manner 
tied  up  with  the  middle  phases.  In  fact,  while  the  three  phases  ap- 
pear as  morphologically  distinct  they  are  not  so  functionally  at  all. 

Another  important  point  for  the  understanding  of  memorial  be- 
havior and  one  which  argues  for  the  continuity  of  such  reaction  is 
the  fact  that  memory  reactions  involve  very  close  connections  be- 
tween specific  responses  and  particular  stimuli  coordinated  with 
them.  A  given  stimulus  must  call  out  directly  a  specific  name  or 
a  specified  act  of  some  non-verbal  sort.  No  substitution  of  response, 
no  new  act  not  previously  begun  and  postponed  may  now  occur  or 
we  are  not  remembering  or  are  remembering  faultily  and  ineffec- 


MEMORY:  A  T BIPHASE  OBJECTIVE  ACTION      627 

tively.  With  respect  to  directness  or  connection  between  stimuli 
and  responses,  memorial  behavior  differs  from  thinking  (another 
type  of  delayed  behavior)  in  which  the  action,  when  it  occurs,  may 
be  indefinitely  determined  by  an  anterior  trial  and  error  procedure. 

To  the  important  points  which  we  have  just  made  concerning 
memory  behavior  segments,  namely,  that  they  operate  between  two 
definite  end  time  points,  and  that  throughout  this  time  a  particular 
coordination  of  stimulus  and  response  is  operating,  we  may  now 
add  a  third  point,  namely,  that  the  time  through  which  the  con- 
tinuous action  operates  may  be  more  or  less  prolonged.  That  is  to 
say,  even  when  memory  reactions  are  intentionally  projected  they 
may  operate  finally  only  after  some  indefinite  time  period.  This 
situation  is  illustrated  by  the  person  who  is  memorizing  some  ma- 
terial for  an  examination  although  he  is  not  fully  informed  as  to 
when  that  examination  is  to  take  place. 

There  remains  now  to  point  out,  that  what  might  appear  plaus- 
ible enough  in  discussing  the  continuous  or  postponing  character 
of  memory  reactions,  when  such  delayed  behavior  is  taken  to  be  a 
final  reaction  (that  is,  when  the  memory  act  is  the  adjustment  or 
adaptation  in  question)  may  equally  well  be  true  when  the  memory 
act  is  precurrent  to  another  act.  In  other  words,  even  when  the 
memory  action  is  only  preliminary  to  some  other  act,  the  postponed 
or  continuous  functioning  is  an  integral  feature  of  the  total  be- 
havior situation.  This  point  is  really  very  important  for  it  illumi- 
nates greatly  the  general  character  of  memory  behavior.  It  is  well 
to  appreciate  the  fact  that  memorial  reactions  constitute  definite 
types  of  psychological  behavior  in  the  sense  that  the  memory  act 
may  be  a  preliminary  recalling  of  information  upon  which  further 
action  is  based  or  it  might  itself  be  the  complete  adaptation  as  in 
reminiscence.  In  this  connection  it  may  be  well  to  point  out  that, 
once  the  second  active  phase  of  a  behavior  segment  is  operating,  the 
additional  problem  arises  whether  there  will  be  a  forward-looking 
result  or  merely  a  backward-looking  one,  that  is,  one  that  merely 
refers  back  to  or  repeats  the  projection  stage  of  memory. 

Corresponding  to  the  precurrent  and  final  character  of  memory 
reactions  are  the  simple  and  complex  characters  of  such  behavior. 
Plainly,  the  precurrent  reactions  will  be  by  far  the  simpler  of  the 
two  types.  In  fact,  the  complex  final  memorial  behavior  segments 
may  be  replete  with  all  sorts  of  component  responses,  many  of 
which  if  functioning  alone  would  be  far  removed  from  the  descrip- 
tion and  name  of  memory  behavior. 


628  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

II.    MEMORY  BEHAVIOR  CONTRASTED  WITH  OTHER  TYPES 

The  fact  that  memory  reactions  are  delayed  and  consequently 
require  substitution  stimuli  constitute  the  essential  criterion  for 
distinguishing  such  reactions  from,  say,  perceptual  responses.  But 
why  contrast  memory  with  perception?  We  answer,  because  it  has 
been  traditionally  held  that  since  in  perceptual  behavior  we  react 
to  whole  objects  although  we  are  in  direct  contact  only  with  some 
phase  or  quality  of  them,  that  we  must  therefore  have  a  memory 
reaction  in  each  perceptual  response.  Now  we  hold  that  because  of 
the  complete  absence  in  perceptual  behavior  of  the  continuous  and 
temporally  distributed  features  of  memory  action  that  the  two  are 
totally  unlike. 

We  assume  that  the  fundamental  feature  of  perceptual  re- 
sponses is  the  fact  that  a  specific  differential  reaction  is  called  out 
by  a  specific  stimulus-object  or  condition  and  that  any  changes  in 
the  stimulus-object  or  in  its  setting  will  bring  about  or  result  in 
some  corresponding  change  in  the  perceptual  reaction  system.  Of 
course,  it  is  quite  true  that  the  reaction  now  made  to  a  perceptual 
object  is  one  that  was  built  up  in  many  cases  to  a  whole  object,  only 
part  of  which  now  calls  out  the  original  response,  but  this  in  no 
wise  involves  any  memory  response.  Tersely  put;  we  do  not  ordi- 
narily remember  that  the  book  we  perceive  has  such  and  such  fea- 
tures on  the  side  we  can  not  now  see,  although  this  contact  with 
the  book  may  involve,  as  in  every  other  perceptual  situation,  defi- 
nite memory  behavior.  That  this  observation  is  sound  readily  ap- 
pears when  we  take  the  case  of  an  orange  or  other  particular  object 
to  which  we  react  without  ever  having  been  in  contact  with  it  be- 
fore. The  act  in  this  illustration  is  a  perceptual  act  but  can  not  be 
a  memorial  action  because  in  the  former  case  we  are  reacting  to  an 
object  with  a  reaction  system  developed  to  these  qualities  (size, 
shape,  color)  present  among  others  (taste,  weight,  texture),  etc. 
Whereas  in  the  case  of  memory  the  original  object  is  not  present 
at  all  but  is  substituted  for.  Moreover,  in  the  case  of  memory  we 
have  a  delayed  or  postponed  reaction.  Because  memory  depends 
upon  a  substitute  stimulus  the  reaction  is  never  exactly  like  a 
former  one  and  gradually  fades.  Also,  owing  to  the  fact  that  a 
number  of  different  absent  objects  may  be  reacted  to  simultaneously, 
our  memory  responses  may  be  exceedingly  unreliable.  When  faulty 
perceptual  reactions  (illusions)  occur  they  are  owing  to  entirely 
different  conditions,  although  some  imperfect  perceptual  reactions 
(hallucinations)  may  be  accounted  for  on  much  the  same  basis. 

Two  types  of  facts  are  implied,  therefore,  in  our  conception  of 
memory  behavior.  In  the  first  place,  we  have  no  room  in  our  de- 


MEMORY:  A  TRI PHASE  OBJECTIVE  ACTION      629 

scription  for  the  sorcerous  reinstatement  of  mental  states  in  the 
remembering  mind  through  a  mysterious  association  of  ideas,  a 
process  usually  made  more  mysterious  still  by  means  of  various 
forms  of  imaginary  neurology.  And  in  the  second  place,  we  abjure 
the  notion  that  memorial  behavior  consists  of  the  mere  fact  of  hav- 
ing a  reaction  system  previously  acquired,  function  later  whenever 
the  adjustment  stimulus  is  presented.  The  latter  fact  is  merely  a 
general  property  or  condition  of  psychological  organisms  and  is  the 
basis  for  all  psychological  responses  and  not  merely  of  memory  be- 
havior. This  reaction  process  that  we  have  just  been  describing  is 
a  much  simpler  fact  than  that  involved  in  memory  and  can  not 
possibly  be  confused  with  the  delayed  or  postponing  of  a  reaction 
system.  Let  us  observe  then,  that  memory  behavior  can  not  be 
identified  either  with  habit  responses  or  with  learning.  For  the 
former  are  behavior  segments  constituting  closely  integrated  re- 
sponses and  stimuli;  so  that  the  appearance  of  the  stimuli  immedi- 
ately arouses  the  correlated  responses.  Indeed,  habits  as  character- 
ized from  the  standpoint  of  promptness  and  immediacy  of  the  total 
response  are  almost  the  opposite  in  type  from  memorial  behavior. 

Now,  so  far  as  learning  is  concerned,  besides  being  merely  a 
coordination  of  responses  and  stimuli,  such  a  reaction  is  presumed 
to  be  a  more  or  less  permanent  acquisition  and  the  more  usual  con- 
dition is  that  it  should  be  so,  whereas  memory  is  in  a  unique  sense 
a  temporal  affair  designed  to  operate  for  a  specific  period  of  time 
only.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  the  rather  unusual  and  universally  ac- 
claimed incompetent  learning  known  as  cramming  answers  much 
more  to  the  description  of  memory  than  any  other  kind.  Further- 
more, whereas  learning  involves  a  single  coordination  between 
stimuli  and  responses,  memory  behavior  comprises  a  special  com- 
bination of  adjustment  and  substitute  stimuli  with  the  given  re- 
sponses. Again,  the  coordination  of  learning  responses  and  stimuli 
are  presumed  to  operate  periodically  while  memory  reactions  func- 
tion continuously.  We  might  say  further  that  learning  reactions 
involve  much  memory  behavior  and  always  do  comprise  some  me- 
morial operations,  but  they  are  not  identical  with  memory  reactions, 
for  learning  behavior  includes  many  other  kinds  of  reaction,  for 
example,  thinking,  reasoning,  perceiving,  imagining,  willing,  etc. 

Incidentally  we  may  here  enter  a  caveat  against  the  assumption 
that  memory  responses  represent  elementary  organic  processes,  very 
frequently  nowadays  referred  to  as  mnemic  processes.  Besides  con- 
necting memory  with  a  very  contentless  abstraction,  this  assumption 
leads  us  to  overlook  the  tremendously  complex  conditions  which 
find  a  place  in  every  memory  situation.  Almost  any  memory  re- 


t;:io  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

sponse  taken  at  random  will  indicate  to  us  a  large  series  of  human 
conditions,  adaptational  needs  and  environmental  stimuli,  all  of 
which  in  their  combination  and  interaction  play  a  part  in  the  pro- 
jection and  recall  phenomena  of  memory. 

III.    PROTECTIVE  AND  RECOLLECTIVE  MEMORY 

Throughout  the  whole  series  of  thousands  of  memory  reactions 
we  can  trace  a  functional  difference  which  may  be  seized  upon  as  a 
distinguishing  mark  to  divide  off  memory  reactions  into  two  broad 
types  which  we  will  name  (1)  projective  and  (2)  recollective  mem- 
ory, respectively.  The  first  type  is  characterized  by  the  fact  that  its 
operation  depends  primarily  upon  the  response  side  of  the  stimulus- 
response  coordination;  that  is  to  say,  the  initiation  of  the  act  de- 
pends to  a  considerable  extent  upon  the  needs  and  desires  or  other 
activities  of  the  person.  The  second  type,  on  the  other  hand,  de- 
pends somewhat  more  definitely  upon  the  stimulating  conditions. 
Because  of  some  intensity  or  strikingness  of  an  event  in  which  the 
person  partakes,  the  memory  activity  is  initiated  and  operates  con- 
tinuously. The  extreme  forms  of  this  type  of  memory  are  those 
cases  in  which,  because  of  a  frightful  experience,  any  slightly  re- 
sembling situation  brings  to  mind  sometimes  in  a  shocking  manner 
the  original  event.  Obviously,  this  distinction  must  be  relative 
but  in  practise  it  is  sufficiently  observable  to  provide  a  criterion. 

Another  and  even  more  relative  distinction  between  projective 
and  recollective  memory  may  be  introduced.  We  may  separate 
them  on  the  basis  of  an  apparently  more  prominent  operation  of 
the  initiatory  and  consummatory  phase  of  the  total  behavior.  In 
the  one  case  (projective)  the  action  appears  to  involve  mainly  the 
initiation  or  projection  of  a  memory  behavior,  while  in  the  other 
case  (recollective),  the  important  factor  seems  to  be  the  recalling 
phase  or  what  is  popularly  called  the  recollecting  or  the  remember- 
ing. Naturally  in  each  case  both  phases  must  be  functionally 
equally  present.  Since  we  are  dealing  with  continuous  action,  the 
apparent  prominence  of  one  or  the  other  phase  may  be  only  seem- 
ingly a  difference,  but  for  purposes  of  classification  at  any  rate, 
we  accept  the  distinction  as  an  actual  practical  difference  in  the 
memory  behavior  types.  We  proceed,  then,  to  discuss  the  two  types 
of  memory  action  separately. 

(1)  Projective  Memory  Acts. — In  this  class  we  might  consider 
two  types  (a)  the  intentional  and  (6)  the  unintentional  projective 
memory  response,  (a)  By  intentional  projective  memory  we  mean 
the  actions  in  which  the  person  purposely  postpones,  suspends  or 


MEMORY:  A  TRIPHASE  OBJECTIVE  ACTION      631 

projects  a  response  into  the  future  to  be  later  performed.  As  illus- 
trations we  might  take  the  situations  in  which  the  person  makes 
an  engagement,  or  arranges  to  do  something  later,  or  memorizes 
some  information  to  be  used  at  a  future  date. 

(&)  By  unintentional  projective  memory  we  refer  to  situations 
in  which  the  person  is  not  spontaneously  involved  in  the  memorial 
action;  either  he  is  disinterested  or  does  it  merely  through  the  in- 
fluence of  a  group  convention,  although  the  person  himself  and  not 
the  stimuli  plays  the  predominant  role  in  the  total  behavior  seg- 
ment. Typical  of  such  memory  reactions  are  the  casual  informa- 
tion behavior  which  involves  acquiring  memory  materials  by  sheer 
contact  with  things. 

(2)  Recollective  Memory  Acts. — Under  the  rubric  of  recollec- 
tive  memory  behavior  we  may  include  three  types,  namely,  (a) 
casual  remembering  or  reminiscence,  (6)  direct  recollection,  and 
(c)  memorial  recovery. 

(a)  By  casual  remembering  we  mean  the  kind  of  activity  in 
which  some  unimportant  and  even  obscure  stimulus  starts  off  a  train 
of  memory  actions  to  absent  things  and  events.  The  whole  proce- 
dure is  unconditioned  by  any  need  or  necessity,  but  once  the  pro- 
cess is  started  it  gains  momentum  and  proceeds  apace.  Each  re- 
covered element  serves  to  arouse  a  further  factor.  On  the  whole, 
the  action  is  passive  at  the  time  and  no  special  practical  value  ac- 
crues to  the  person,  although  it  may  be  the  source  of  no  end  of 
amusement  or  depressive  uneasiness.  That  is  to  say,  the  ongoing  of 
this  activity  may  be  of  tremendous  importance  in  the  way  of  stimu- 
lating the  person.  So  far  as  the  surrounding  objects  are  concerned, 
however,  no  change  in  them  need  be  effected.  Again,  the  whole 
procedure  may  be  greatly  facilitated  by  the  relaxed  and  inactive 
condition  of  the  person.  We  can  not  at  this  point  refrain  from 
mentioning  again  that  the  action  represents  a  consummation  of  a 
stimulus  and  response  connection  previously  organized. 

(&)  In  direct  recollection  the  need  to  have  some  information 
such  as  a  name  or  event,  or  when  we  must  recover  a  lost  article, 
stimulates  us  to  bring  about  the  operation  of  a  consummatory  phase 
of  a  memory  behavior.  Here  the  primary  emphasis  is  upon  the  re- 
call for  the  purpose  of  achieving  some  practical  result,  although 
when  the  initiatory  phase  of  the  action  was  started  there  was  no 
emphasis  upon  the  person's  participation  in  the  situation.  This 
type  of  memory  is  well  illustrated  by  the  recollection  of  a  witness 
in  a  court  trial,  though  in  this  particular  case  the  memorial  be- 
havior may  not  result  in  any  apparent  direct  consequences.  The 
criterion,  however,  for  this  kind  of  memory  remains  the  instru- 
mental recollective  one. 


632  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

(c)  Contrasting  with  the  type  of  memory  just  discussed,  me- 
morial recovery  represents  the  activity  in  which  the  consummately 
phase  of  a  memory  reaction  is  made  to  operate  primarily  for  the 
purpose  of  the  action  itself  rather  than  to  effect  some  change  in 
surrounding  objects.  In  memorial  recovery  the  aim  is  to  effect  some 
change  of  condition  in  the  person,  the  removal  of  a  weight  from 
one's  conscience,  as  in  ritualistic  confession  or  in  medical  psycho- 
analysis. It  was  in  connection  with  this  capacity  to  live  over  ex- 
periences that  Aristotle  developed  his  theory  of  esthetic  Catharsis. 

IV.    INFORMATIONAL  AND  PERFORMATIVE  MEMORY  ACTS 

Implicit  in  our  distinction  of  memory  behavior  just  discussed 
as  well  as  in  the  rest  of  our  description  lies  another  differentiation 
which  we  must  bring  to  the  surface.  It  is,  namely,  the  distinction 
between  memory  acts  which  constitute  some  actual  work  to  be  done 
(performative)  and  memorial  behavior  which  merely  adapts  the 
person  to  some  past  event  or  action  (informational).  In  the  latter 
case,  the  person  may  merely  know  something  about  past  conditions. 
In  some  cases,  of  course,  the  information  memory  reaction  may  be 
a  preliminary  step  to  a  future  action  dated  from  the  time  of  the 
last  or  consummatory  period  of  the  informational  memory  behavior 
segment,  but  in  this  case  we  assume  the  new  action  to  belong  to  a 
different  behavior  segment.  The  whole  distinction  which  we  are 
making  hinges  upon  the  functional  character  of  the  behavior  seg- 
ment in  which  the  memorial  action  plays  a  part.  Thus,  memorizing 
might  be  considered  as  a  memorial  action  midway  between  the  in- 
formational and  performative  sort. 

To  a  considerable  extent  we  may  use  the  distinction  we  have 
just  made  as  a  differentiation  between  memory  in  which  we  are  defi- 
nitely aware  of  the  operation  and  purpose  of  the  entire  act  (in- 
formational) and  cases  in  which  we  remember  without  so  definitely 
employing  the  memory  activity  to  bring  about  a  necessary  or  de- 
sirable further  result  (performative).  It  is  only  proper  to  say 
here  that  the  informational  memory  may  be  considered  as  of  the 
maximum  degree  of  awareness  while  the  performative  memory  can 
be  so  extremely  lacking  in  awareness  or  intention  that  it  fits  the 
popular  term  subconscious. 

V.    How  MEMORY  REACTIONS  OPERATE 

The  operation  of  memory  responses  consists  primarily  of  the 
operation  of  the  two  more  definitely  observable  of  the  three  phases 
described  in  an  earlier  part  of  this  paper,  to  wit,  the  initiatory  and 


MEMORY:  A  TRIPHASE  OBJECTIVE  ACTION      633 

consummatory  stages.  The  first  action  initiates  or  projects  delayed 
or  continuous  responses,  while  the  second  consists  of  the  consum- 
mation of  the  suspended  responses  through  the  functioning  of  a 
substitute  stimulus.  This  second  process  consists  of  the  excitation 
of  the  delayed  response  by  some  stimulus-object  or  condition  which 
operates  in  place  of  the  original  or  adjustment  stimulus  and  which 
calls  out  the  response  to  that  original  stimulus.  We  may  take 
advantage  of  this  functional  division  of  the  memory  behavior  seg- 
ment and  discuss  each  phase  in  turn. 

(1)  The  Initiatory  or  Protective  Phase. — In  general,  this  phase 
consists  of  connecting  up  three  things,  of  organizing  a  tripartite 
association.  This  association  connects  up  some  act  with  an  adjust- 
ment and  a  substitute  stimulus.  In  different  situations  one  or  the 
other  of  these  features  stands  out  more  prominently.  For  example, 
in  some  cases  the  association  of  the  response  with  the  adjustment 
stimulus  is  most  prominent.  This  would  be  true  in  all  cases  where 
the  delayed  memory  response  consists  of  making  an  engagement 
(typical  projective  response).  Again,  in  other  cases  the  associa- 
tion between  the  adjustment  and  substitute  stimuli  seems  to  be  most 
prominent  as  is  true  whenever  we  employ  a  mnemonic  system,  that 
is  to  say,  when  we  remember  the  days  in  the  month  by  verse.  Here 
the  verse  constitutes  the  substitute  stimulus  and  the  days  of  the 
month  the  adjustment  stimulus.  In  still  other  cases  the  connection 
between  the  response  and  the  substitute  stimulus  appears  most 
prominent.  This  is  true  in  case  of  an  engagement  in  which  the  re- 
sponse seems  to  be  connected  with  the  day  of  the  week  rather  than 
with  the  person,  situation,  or  event  to  which  we  are  preparing  to 
adjust  ourselves. 

This  summary  statement  can  obviously  be  looked  upon  as  the 
barest  sort  of  outline  of  the  initiation  of  a  continuous  or  memory 
reaction.  In  fact,  a  fuller  content  description  would  necessarily  in- 
clude details  concerning  the  nature  of  the  specific  future  act  in- 
volved, besides  the  description  of  the  exact  objects,  persons  and 
events  serving  as  the  adjustment  and  substitute  stimuli. 

The  point  to  the  triple  association  is  plain  and  follows  from  the 
general  nature  of  memory  action.  Because  the  action  is  projected 
and  later  to  be  completed  when  the  adjustment  stimulus  will  no 
longer  be  present,  it  is  essential  that  there  be  connections  made  be- 
tween what  is  to  be  the  consummatory  action  and  other  stimuli 
capable  of  arousing  the  action  to  the  adjustment  stimulus.  But  in 
order  that  one  object  or  condition  should  be  capable  of  substituting 
for  another  object  or  condition,  it  is  necessary  that  the  two  objects 
be  connected  with  each  other  as  well  as  with  the  projected  act.  The 


634  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

entire  process  of  connection  spoken  of  here  is  merely  the  ordinary 
process  of  psychological  association. 

(2)  The  Consummatory  or  Recollective  Phase. — The  operation 
of  the  delayed  phase  of  the  memory  reaction  consists  essentially  in 
its  arousal  by  the  appearance  of  the  object  serving  as  a  substitute 
stimulus  or  by  the  reacting  person  otherwise  coming  into  contact 
with  a  substitute  stimulus.  In  consequence,  this  contact  with  the 
substitute  stimulus  may  be  a  definitely  arranged  affair  as  in  the 
case  of  employing  a  memorandum  book  for  the  purpose,  or  it  may 
consist  of  a  very  casual  contact. 

This  whole  matter  of  the  consummation  of  a  memory  act  is  well 
illustrated  by  the  fact  that  forgetting  is  a  direct  function  of  the 
deliberateness  or  casualness  of  the  contact  of  the  person  with  the 
substitute  stimulus.  This  point  may  also  be  illustrated  by  observ- 
ing that  the  possibility  of  remembering  is  a  function  of  the  num- 
ber of  substitute  stimuli  connected  with  the  adjustment  stimulus. 
The  more  substitute  stimuli  that  function  in  any  specific  situation 
the  more  probable  it  is  that  there  will  be  no  forgetting,  the  more 
probable,  in  other  words,  that  the  memory  response  will  operate. 

The  reason  why  a  memory  response  is  more  likely  to  occur  when 
there  are  more  substitute  stimuli  than  when  there  are  less  is  be- 
cause of  the  obvious  greater  possibility  for  contact  between  the 
person  and  the  stimulus.  That  is  to  say,  the  adjustment  stimulus 
is  more  thoroughly  represented.  This  fact  of  making  possible  the 
operation  of  the  consummatory  phase  of  a  memory  reaction,  or  let 
us  say,  in  short,  remembering  at  all,  is  usually  referred  to  as  reten- 
tiveness.1  The  fact  that  certain  information  is  retained  depends 
upon  the  number  of  objects  and  other  facts  with  which  it  is  con- 
nected. For  this  reason  it  is  generally  recognized  that  the  more 
systematically  organized  one 's  knowledge  is,  that  is  to  say,  the  more 
connections  made  between  substitute  stimuli  and  the  knowing  re- 
sponse, the  more  capable  one  is  in  this  kind  of  situation  and  the 
greater  facility  one  has  in  the  employment  of  such  information. 

We  might  emphasize  here  that  this  factor  of  retentiveness  is 
decidedly  a  matter  of  associational  connection  and  thus  is  justified 
the  traditional  belief  that  memorial  behavior  is  to  the  largest  ex- 
tent a  fact  of  association.  More  important  it  is,  however,  to  observe 
that  the  associational  process  is  at  every  point  a  thoroughly  and  com- 
pletely objective  series  of  happenings.  Memorial  behavior,  we  re- 

*  The  writer  here  wishes  to  pay  a  just  tribute  to  the  whole  line  of  psycholo- 
gist* who  have  observed  the  serial  (three  or  four  members)  functioning  of  a 
memory  behavior  segment,  although  they  do  not  emphasize  the  functional  con- 
tinuity of  the  members,  nor  describe  them  in  an  objective  manner. 


MEMORY:  A  T BIPHASE  OBJECTIVE  ACTION      635 

peat,  is  without  doubt  a  matter  of  associational  connection,  even 
if  it  is  true  that  in  some  cases  as  in  cramming  or  the  remembering 
of  a  thing  but  for  a  brief  period,  only  a  very  limited  number  of 
retention  substitute  stimuli  exist  and  operate. 

In  the  operation  of  memory  behavior  segments  a  series  of  specific 
forms  of  operation  may  be  observed  to  occur.  These  forms  may 
involve  primarily  either  the  stimulus  or  the  response  and  may  be 
described  as  follows. 

(a)  Stimulus  Forms 

(1)  Some    Object   or  Event   Operates   throughout   the   Whole 
Behavior  Segment. — Here  the  substitution  and  adjustment  stimuli 
are  both  the  same  object,  that  is,  I  remember  to  react  to  some  ob- 
ject because  I  now  see  it  or  remember  to  tell  some  person  something 
I  agreed  to  tell  him  because  his  presence  itself  reminds  me  of  the 
fact.    Probably  this  form  of  memory  action  would  be  most  common 
in  the  segments  which  we  have  agreed  to  name  the  recollective  reac- 
tions. 

(2)  Another  Object  Becomes  the  Adequate  Stimulus. — In  these 
segments  a  different  object  from  the  one  to  which  the  response  is  to 
be  made  initiates  the  consummatory  phase  of  the  response.     This 
form  of  memory  may  safely  be  called  the  typical  sort  and  it  un- 
doubtedly constitutes  a  larger  series  of  actual  memory  behavior 
segments.    Moreover,  the  reactions  of  this  type  constitute  the  most 
effective  of  our  memory  behavior.    Because  of  the  range  of  objects 
that  can  serve  to  arouse  the  reaction  the  memory  behavior  can  be 
carried  over  great  stretches  of  time  and  place.    A  striking  example 
of  the  power  of  such  memory  actions  as  we  are  now  discussing  is 
supplied  us  in  the  operation  of  the  extremely  complex  behavior  in 
which  we  use  printed  and  other  symbolic  records  to  incite  memory 
reactions  to  function. 

(&)  Reaction  Forms 

(1)  Same  Reaction  System. — Many  of  our  memory  reactions 
operate  through  a  postdated  functioning  of  the  same  reaction  sys- 
tem or  response  pattern.  This  reaction  system  or  pattern  is  the 
original  projected  action  which  is  connected  with  a  specific  stimu- 
lus, whether  it  be  the  same  or  a  different  object.  Illustrative  of 
this  form  of  memory  reaction  is  the  recalling  of  a  name,  a  date  or 
any  type  of  information.  The  effectiveness  of  the  reaction  depends 
entirely  upon  the  literalness  with  which  the  original  projected  act 
operates  after  its  period  of  actual  delay.  Possibly  this  type  of 


636  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

reaction  does  not  comprise  the  most  important  of  our  memory  re- 
actions, since  we  include  here  the  whole  series  of  rote  memory  re- 
sponses. 

(2)  Different  or  Partially  Different  Reaction  Systems. — A  great 
number  of  our  memory  reactions  do  not  involve  necessarily  a  simple 
exact  repetition  of  a  specific  reaction  system.  Rather  a  more  or 
less  greater  freedom  is  allowed  us  in  the  action.  This  fact  arises 
from  the  circumstance  that  these  types  of  memory  behavior  repre- 
sent adaptation  to  cultural  conditions  or  objects  and  not  to  specific 
physical  objects.  Nor  are  these  reactions  very  definite  direct  ad- 
aptations, such  as  going  to  a  certain  place  at  a  given  time ;  instead 
they  involve  situations  in  which  a  novel  or  constructive  action 
carries  out  the  purpose  of  the  situation.  The  projection  and  later 
carrying  out  of  a  scientific  investigation,  the  execution  of  a  literary 
or  other  artistic  commission,  in  so  far  as  they  involve  a  projection 
and  a  later  operation  of  a  memory  reaction,  all  illustrate  the  ex- 
treme forms  of  memory  reactions  of  the  present  class.  From  these 
more  complex  substitutable  responses  we  may  trace  out  a  descend- 
ing series  which  may  run  down  to  substituted  reactions  differing 
very  little  in  morphological  character  from  the  action  operating  at 
the  time  the  memory  behavior  is  in  the  projection  stage. 

VI.    RECOGNITION  AND  MEMORY 

Psychologists  have  always  recognized  that  memorial  behavior 
essentially  and  intimately  involves  recognition.  The  relationship 
is  indeed  a  close  one  although  recognition  is  not  exclusively  a  fea- 
ture of  memory.  Perceptual  reactions  are  no  less  closely  connected 
with  recognition  behavior.  That  recognition  reactions,  however, 
have  historically  been  presumed  as  most  closely  connected  with  mem- 
ory is  accounted  for,  we  believe,  by  the  fact  that  in  complex  me- 
morial behavior  recognition  assuredly  occupies  a  very  strategic  and 
prominent  position.  Unless  we  are  to  leave  our  description  of  mem- 
ory in  too  fragmentary  a  form  we  must  then  indicate  the  exact 
operation  of  the  recognition  function  in  memory. 

But  first  let  us  point  out  why  recognition  appears  to  be  so 
prominent  a  factor  in  such  behavior.  Both  the  clue  and  solution 
are  found  in  {he  continuous  and  prolonged  character  of  memory  re- 
actions. In  other  words,  there  must  be  some  marks  or  signs  of  connec- 
tion of  the  second  phase  with  the  first.  The  point  is,  that  the  second 
phase,  although  an  integral  part  of  the  memorial  behavior  segment, 
may  still  be  detached  in  whole  or  part  from  the  first  phase  of  action. 
Now  aside  from  the  essential  or  universal  fact  that  the  two  pha- 
ses must  occur  in  order  that  a  memory  act  shall  be  completed,  it  is 


MEMORY:  A  TRIPE  AS  E  OBJECTIVE  ACTION      637 

frequently  necessary  that  the  person  performing  the  action  should 
appreciate  overtly  the  connection  between  the  two  phases.  How 
frequently  it  is  necessary  for  this  overt  appreciation  of  the  continu- 
ity of  the  memory  behavior  to  occur  depends  upon  the  general 
overtness  of  the  memory  action.  That  is  to  say,  whenever  the  per- 
son is  fully  aware  of  the  need  for  an  operation  of  the  memorial  re- 
action, then  the  recognition  factor  is  essential.  Incidentally  there 
issues  forth  here  two  related  points  that  must  be  at  least  briefly  in- 
spected. In  the  first  place,  not  all  memorial  behavior  requires  a 
recognition  factor;  only  the  more  elaborate  sorts  of  memory  do  so. 
And  in  the  second  place,  the  recognition  feature  may  be  of  differ- 
ent degrees.  It  remains  now  for  us  to  describe  briefly  the  process 
of  recognition  and  to  indicate  how  it  varies  in  its  operation. 

Recognition  in  general  is  a  meaning  reaction ;  that  is  to  say,  the 
final  action  to  a  stimulus  is  preceded  by  a  determining  action  which 
lends  color  and  direction  to  the  succedent  or  final  act.  Because  a 
memory  action  involves  a  minimum  of  two  operations  (projection 
or  consummatory)  and  also  two  stimuli  (adjustmental  and  substi- 
tute) the  stage  is  well  set  for  the  performance  of  recognition  ac- 
tion. To  illustrate  with  the  simplest  case,  when  the  substitute 
stimulus  appears  there  may  occur  a  single  direct  response  to  the 
adjustment  stimulus;  here  we  have  memory  without  recognition. 
But  if  in  this  behavior  segment  some  implicit  or  overt  response 
precedes,  either  necessarily  or  fortuitously  the  reaction  to  the  ad- 
justment stimulus,  why  then  we  assume  that  the  individual  recog- 
nizes either  the  reaction  or  to  what  the  reaction  is  made.  In  other 
words,  the  substitution  stimulus-object  becomes  a  sign  for  what- 
ever thing  we  presume  to  be  signified  (act  or  adjustment  object). 
As  in  every  other  case  of  meaning  behavior  the  recognition  factors 
or  reaction  systems  are  to  a  considerable  extent,  though  of  course 
not  exclusively,  implicit  responses  and  verbal  reactions,  and  pos- 
sibly the  latter  are  most  characteristic  in  memory  behavior.  Very 
familiar  is  the  functioning  of  exclamatory  reactions  in  memorial 
recognition,  "I  see"  being  a  most  frequent  meaning  reaction,  al- 
though none  the  less  potent  are  subvocal  language  responses. 

Besides  the  appreciation  by  the  person  that  the  stimulus-object 
initiating  the  memory  behavior,  and  the  stimulus-object  (substitu- 
tion) operating  in  the  culmination  of  the  act  are  related  to  each 
other  and  to  the  act,  there  are  still  other  factors  involved  in  the 
more  complex  forms  of  recognition.  In  addition  to  those  enumer- 
ated features,  the  individual  may  also  realize  his  own  place  in  the 
total  memory  situation.  To  be  explicit,  the  person  himself  becomes 
an  additional  stimulus,  or  more  frequently  assumes  the  function 


638  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  the  setting  of  one  or  more  of  the  stimuli  involved.  The  most 
complex  form  of  recognition  is  the  case  in  which  the  individual 
continues  to  project  himself  into  every  feature  of  the  continuous 
memory  response.  It  is  in  such  cases  as  these  that  the  person's 
own  responses  constitute  a  good  share  of  the  memory  behavior  and 
condition  directly  the  continuity  features  of  such  behavior. 

Now  we  might  point  out  that  in  the  complex  recognition  memory 
reactions  the  person  may  not  only  play  a  part  in  the  total  behavior 
when  the  recollective  phase  operates,  but  may  also  play  such  a  part 
in  the  initiatory  phase.  Instead  of  the  person  appreciating  that 
the  response  has  in  fact  been  continued,  has  reached  culmination 
and  that  the  final  response  has  answered  the  purpose,  he  may  like- 
wise appreciate  the  necessity  for  and  the  actual  occurrence  of  a 
projection  act.  Recognition  of  the  nature  and  needs  of  projecting 
a  response  to  be  later  consummated  depends,  of  course,  upon  previ- 
ous experiences  with  similar  situations. 

VII.    THE  STIMULI  FOB  MEMORY  REACTIONS 

In  descriptions  of  memory  behavior  the  specifications  of  stimuli 
and  stimulation  conditions  appear  to  be  of  more  significance  than 
in  other  types  of  action,  although  stimuli  are  of  necessity  integral 
factors  in  all  psychological  acts.  In  the  first  place,  because  me- 
morial retention  consists  of  the  interconnection  of  responses  with 
adjustment  and  substitute  stimuli,  the  stimuli  are  more  uniquely 
phases  of  the  total  behavior  situation.  In  the  second  place,  since 
memorial  behavior  comprises  two  phases  operating  at  different 
times,  the  stimuli  features  of  such  reactions  loom  large.  And  fi- 
nally, memorial  reactions  are  responses  of  occasion ;  so  that  combina- 
tions of  responses  function  together  and  for  that  reason  the  stimuli 
obtrude  themselves  upon  the  student  who  attempts  to  analyze  such 
behavior.  To  illustrate,  when  taking  an  examination  the  fact  that 
we  are  undergoing  examination  is  in  general  a  stimulus  for  me- 
morial behavior,  while  the  specific  ideas  or  facts  recalled  are  brought 
out  by  the  particular  questions  which  we  may  call  the  substitute 
stimuli  for  the  objects  and  events  around  which  the  examination  is 
centered. 

In  general,  then,  we  find  the  stimuli  factors  exceedingly  con- 
spicuous in  descriptions  of  memorial  behavior.  We  may  proceed 
now  to  point  out  some  of  the  more  prominent  forms  of  memorial 
stimuli  and  we  might,  because  of  the  prominence  of  the  recollective 
phase  in  memorial  behavior,  put  the  problem  into  the  following 
form.  What  kind  of  objects  and  conditions  can  serve  as  substitute 
stimuli  f 


BOOK  REVIEWS  639 

Among  such  stimuli  we  find  of  course  objects  and  events.  Any 
object  or  event  connected  with  some  other  object  or  event  to  which 
we  respond  without  its  being  present  may  now  serve  to  arouse  a  re- 
sponse to  that  non-present  object.2  The  same  thing  is  true  of  the 
setting  of  an  object  or  event.  A  time,  place  or  object  setting  may 
serve  as  a  substitute  stimulus  to  induce  a  reaction  to  some  adjust- 
ment stimulus-object  which  was  at  some  previous  time  connected 
with  that  setting.  Very  instructive  is  the  observation  here  that  a 
thing  may  serve  as  a  substitute  stimulus  for  itself,  as  in  the  case 
of  some  object  stimulating  a  recollection  of  some  past  experience 
with  it. 

Again  persons  constitute  a  large  part  of  our  memorial  stimuli. 
This  is  true  for  several  reasons;  first,  a  large  part  of  our  behavior 
in  general  involves  contacts  with  persons  and  in  consequence  the 
latter  may  substitute  for  each  other  as  memorial  stimuli.  More- 
over, because  much  of  our  memorial  activity  consists  of  informa- 
tional reactions  the  stimuli  thereto  consist  of  language  activities  of 
persons.  Besides  the  language  reactions  of  other  persons,  one's 
own  language  responses  are  a  potent  source  of  memory  behavior. 
Nor  do  the  language  acts  exhaust  the  list  of  substitute  stimuli,  since 
our  observation  reveals  numerous  other  of  our  reactions  that  serve 
in  similar  capacities. 

J.  E.  KANTOE. 
INDIANA  UNIVERSITY. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

Dodi  Ve-Nechdi  (Uncle  and  Nephew}  the  work  of  Berachya  Hanak- 
dan.  Edited  from  MSS.  at  Munich  and  Oxford,  with  an  Eng- 
lish translation,  introduction,  etc.;  also  English  translation  from 
the  Latin  of  Adelard  of  Bath's  Qucestiones  Naturales.  HER- 
MANN GOLLANCZ.  Oxford  University  Press,  1920.  Pp.  xxii  -f 
220. 

Berachya  Hanakdan — a  Jewish  scholar  of  the  thirteenth  cen- 
tury— was  lost  track  of  by  the  historians  even  though  he  seems  to 
have  played  a  prominent  role  in  medieval  literature.  The  Fox 
Fables  were  his  only  printed  work  before  1902,  when  Professor 
Gollancz  edited  and  translated  some  of  his  manuscripts  and  entitled 
them  Ethical  Treatises.  These  treatises,  though  regarded  by  Gol- 

2  At  this  point  we  find  in  the  actual  operation  of  psychological  facts  a 
justification  of  Dewey's  contention  that  knowledge  involves  a  continuity  of  ob- 
jects and  events.  Cf.  Dewey's  "Eealism  without  Monism  or  Dualism,"  this 
JOURNAL,  XIX,  pp.  309,  351. 


t.io  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

lancz  and  others  as  a  compendium  of  Saadya,  Bachya,  and  Gabirol, 
are  marked,  however,  with  more  original  thinking  than  appears  on 
the  surface.  Berachya  must  have  been  guided  in  the  choice  of  ex- 
cerpts by  some  ulterior  motive.  One  may  venture  to  assume  that 
he  desired  to  clear  philosophy  from  too  abstract  thinking  and  give 
it  a  more  practical  bent.  Hence  his  emphasis  on  ethical  problems 
on  the  one  hand,  and  his  elimination  of  metaphysical  subtleties  on 
the  other.  His  treatises  are  pregnant  with  pragmatic  philosophy. 

Berachya 's  Dodi  Ve-Nechdi  is  an  adaptation  of  the  Quc&stiones 
Naturales  of  Adelard  of  Bath.  It  treats  the  same  questions  and 
under  the  same  form  of  a  dialogue  between  an  uncle  and  nephew. 
These  questions  deal  with  various  branches  of  natural  science  and 
philosophy.  They  embrace  plants,  animals,  man  and  the  physical 
conditions  of  the  universe.  Like  all  medieval  thinking,  they  are  a 
juxtaposition  of  pertinent  questions  still  honored  today,  with  futile 
and  insignificant  ones.1  To  the  modern  mind  the  futile  ones  are 
perhaps  the  more  fascinating  as  they  are  indications  of  the  progress 
philosophy  has  made  in  gradually  disentangling  pertinent  from 
sterile  queries. 

The  Qucestiones  Naturales  as  well  as  the  Dodi  Ve-Nechdi  seem 
to  me  to  have  been  undertaken  in  a  spirit  of  reform,  in  the  hope  of 
giving  a  new  impetus  to  the  thought  of  the  time.  The  Arabian  sci- 
ences were  still  new  in  the  west  of  Europe  and  decried  by  many. 
Adelard  hoped  that  in  introducing  them,  he  would  open  new  vistas 
for  his  generation  which  he  describes  as  lax  in  morals  and  enslaved 
in  thought.  Berachya  also  seems  to  have  been  animated  by  a  desire 
to  broaden  the  Jewish  horizon  with  the  sciences  of  the  time.  Hence 
he  used  the  Qucestiones  Naturales  as  his  reference  work.  Much 
divergence  could  not  be  expected  in  a  period  when  science  was  but 
a  crystallized  and  closed  scheme  statically  transferred  from  one 
language  into  another.  Whatever  related  to  natural  sciences 
Berachya  copied  freely  from  Adelard;  but  when  touching  upon 
moral  or  spiritual  philosophy  he  followed,  I  think,  his  own  line  of 
thought.  Such  an  assumption  would  account  for  the  striking  simi- 
larities, as  well  as  for  the  divergencies  noticeable  in  the  two  works. 

»  Such  as:  "Why  of  all  the  organs  of  a  man's  body  is  it  the  eye  that  seest" 
"Why  human  beings  do  not  have  horns  t" 
"Why  is  the  nose  above  the  mouth  f" 
"Why  does  the  hair  fall  off  from  the  side  of  the  facet" 
"Why  are  not  the  eyes  in  the  back  of  the  headf  " 

"Why  is  the  nostril  the  organ  of  smell,  the  palate  the  organ  of  taste,  and 
the  hand  the  organ  of  touch  f" 

"Granted  that  the  stars  are  alive  on  what  food  do  they  livef  " 


BOOK  REVIEWS  641 

The  scholarly  arrangement  of  Professor  Gollancz's  work  makes 
it  easy  to  prosecute  a  comparative  study  between  the  two  authors. 
He  incorporates  in  this  volume  a  translation  of  Adelard's  Quces- 
tiones  Naturales.  This  is  the  first  English  translation  from  the  only 
existing  Latin  edition  of  1480.  At  the  head  of  each  chapter  in  the 
translation  of  the  Hebrew  manuscript,  he  indicates  the  correspond- 
ing chapter  in  Adelard's  original.  He  also  appends  at  the  end  of 
his  introduction  a  table  indicating  the  relation  between  the  respec- 
tive chapters  in  the  corresponding  works.  The  scholarly  introduc- 
tion as  well  as  the  pleasant  and  facile  style  of  the  translation, 
faithfully  rendered,  greatly  enhance  the  value  of  this  volume  which 
is  an  interesting  contribution  to  medieval  literature. 

NIMA  H.  ADLERBLUM. 
NEW  YORK  CITY. 

Readings  in  Philosophy.  Compiled  by  Albert  Edwin  Avey.  Co- 
lumbus, Ohio:  R.  G.  Adams  &  Co.  1921.  xii-f  683  pp. 
The  Emotions.  JAMES  and  LANGE.  Edited  by  Knight  Dunlap. 
Baltimore :  Williams  &  Wilkins  Co.  1922.  135  pp. 
Avey 's  anthology  is  intended  as  a  supplement  to  an  introductory 
course  in  philosophy,  "a  fairly  representative  collection  of  the 
classic  passages  of  philosophical  literature"  (v).  The  choice  in- 
cludes portions  from  Plato,  Crawley,  Frazer,  Spencer,  Diogenes 
Laertius,  St.  Matthew,  Aristotle,  Sextus  Empiricus,  Corinthians, 
Hume,  St.  Thomas,  Spinoza,  Exodus,  Comte  and  a  number  of  other 
writers.  They  are  arranged  under  a  variety  of  heads  including 
Philosophy  of  History,  Epistemology,  The  Status  of  Values,  Meta- 
physics, Medieval  Philosophy,  Kant,  Pluralism,  Mysticism,  The 
Personality,  Mission  and  Influence  of  Socrates,  et  al.  The  passages 
are  necessarily  short,  cut  off  from  their  context,  and  often  without 
very  clear  relationship  to  the  chapter  headings.  For  example,  in 
"The  Differentiation  of  Philosophy  and  Science  from  Religion" 
we  have  twelve  of  Francis  Bacon's  Native  Fallacies  plus  forty-six 
Fragments  from  Diel's  Vorsokratiker.  Yet  the  collection  serves  a 
purpose — however  much  it  may  suggest  Pope's  line  concerning  the 
Pierian  Spring — in  tempting  an  occasional  student  to  deeper 
draughts. 

The  chief  advantage  in  the  reprint  of  the  James-Lange  essays 
on  the  emotions — the  first  of  a  series  of  "Psychological  Classics" 
edited  by  Knight  Dunlap — lies  in  the  easier  accessibility  of  Lange's 
monograph.  The  translation  is  made  by  I.  A.  Haupt  from  Kurella  's 
Vber  Bemiithsbewegungen  which  appeared  in  1887,  two  years  after 


642  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  Danish  original.  French  translations  are  also  in  existence,  but 
hitherto  psychologists  without  knowledge  of  these  languages  have 
not  had  direct  access  to  Lange  's  contribution. 

The  other  two  essays  are:  first,  a  reprint  from  Mind,  1884, 
"What  is  an  Emotion?",  James'  first  discussion,  and  secondly, 
Chapter  XXV  of  the  Psychology.  These,  of  course,  overlap  to  a 
considerable  extent  but  there  is  some  convenience  in  having  them 
together.  Brief  biographical  notes  of  James  and  Lange  are  con- 
tributed in  the  Editor's  Preface. 

JOHN  M.  WABBEKE. 
MOUNT  HOLYOKE  COLLEGE. 

Hugo  Miinsterberg,  His  Life  and  His  Work.    MARGARET  MUNSTER- 

BERQ.    New  York  and  London :  D.  Appleton  &  Co.    1922.    x  -J- 

448  pp. 

Almost  one  exclaims,  "Nessun  maggior  dolore"  on  glancing 
through  this  book.  I  remember  with  what  satisfaction  James  an- 
nounced to  his  class  in  psychology  that  Miinsterberg  was  coming 
to  Harvard  to  take  charge  of  the  psychological  laboratory.  And  I 
remember,  as  one  of  it,  the  eager  interest  of  Miinsterberg 's  first 
group  of  students,  in  beginning  experimental  psychology  under  the 
guidance  of  the  famous  new  professor.  And  I  remember  the  great 
affection  and  high  esteem  felt  for  Miinsterberg  by  Koyce  in  those 
first  years;  and  when  Miinsterberg  seemed  likely  to  be  seriously  ill, 
the  great  concern  of  us  all ;  we  were  so  sure  then  of  what  Miinster- 
berg's  coming  meant  to  Harvard. 

The  book  idealizes  a  most  unhappy  history,  but  it  is  an  act  of 
loyalty  and  affection  by  a  daughter.  Those  who  esteemed  Profes- 
sor Miinsterberg  to  the  end  will  thank  the  writer  for  her  work. 
Others,  and  there  are  so  many  of  them,  will  declare  it  all  out  of 
perspective,  giving  no  idea  whatever  of  Miinsterberg 's  real  rela- 
tion both  to  Harvard  and  to  America  in  the  latter  part  of  his  life. 
There  is,  of  course,  much  information  about  Miinsterberg 's  life  and 
writings. 

W.  T.  BUSH. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

THE  PHILOSOPHICAL  REVIEW.  Vol.  XXXI,  No.  5.  On  the  Mean- 
ing of  Value :  H.  D.  Oakeley.  The  True,  The  Good  and  The  Beauti- 
ful: H.  R.  Marshall.  A  Comparison  of  the  Scientific  Method  and 
Achievement  of  Aristotle  and  Bacon:  W.  M.  Dickie.  Discussion: 
7  -J-  5  =  12 :  O.  W.  Cunningham. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  643 

LA  CIENCIA  TOMISTA.  Ano  XIV,  No.  LXXVII.  La  Canonization 
de  los  Santos  y  la  fe  divina :  Marin-8ola.  Fray  Diego  de  Deza,  cam- 
peon  de  la  doctrina  de  Santo  Tomas :  Garcia.  El  merito  teologico  y 
sus  divisiones :  Lumbreras. 

ZEITSCHRIFT  FUR  PSYCHOLOGY.  Bd.  90,  Heft  1  u.  2.  Zur 
Theorie  der  stroboskopischen  Bewegungen:  F.  Hildebrand.  Zur 
Psychophysik  der  Geradheit:  E.  Rubin.  Soziale  Verhaltnisse  bei 
Vogeln:  T.  Schjelderup-Ebbe. 

EEVUE  PHILOSOPHIQUE.  Annee  47,  Nos.  9  et  10.  La  notion 
d'objet  et  1'evolution  de  la  physique  contemporaine :  A.  Rey.  L'idee 
de  la  force  mecanique  dans  le  systeme  de  Descartes:  H.  Carteron. 
Sur  une  pretendue  illusion  de  la  memoire.  R.  Lacroze.  "W.  James 
d  'apres  sa  correspondance :  J.  Wahl. 

RWISTA  DI  PSICOLOGIA.  Anno  XVIII,  Nos.  2-3.  La  psicologia 
religiosa  contemporanea :  S.  De  Sanctis.  L'esame  della  memoria 
nei  fanciulli  normali:  E.  Torriani  e  G.  Corberi.  Note  sulla  "scala 
Metrica"  di  Binet  e  Simon  e  sulP  "esame  psicologico  summario"  di 
Francia  e  Ferrari:  G.  Vidoni.  Le  leggi  della  scrittura  speculare 
ed  il  loro  rapporto  col  mancinismo :  A.  Knipfer.  Attitudini  innate 
e  attitudini  acquisite:  0.  Decroly.  La  Superstizione :  G.  Guggen- 
heim. Efficacia  educativa  del  dolore :  E.  Pietrosi. 

MIND.  Vol.  XXXI,  No.  124.  Professor  Alexander's  Theory  of 
Sense  Perception:  G.  F.  Stout.  Is  the  Conception  of  the  Uncon- 
scious of  Value  in  Psychology?:  G.  C.  Field,  F.  Aveling,  and  J. 
Laird.  Are  History  and  Science  different  Kinds  of  Knowledge?: 
R.  G.  Collingwood,  A.  E.  Taylor  and  F.  C.  S.  Schiller.  Symbolism 
as  a  Metaphysical  Principle :  W.  Temple.  Discussion :  Physics  and 
Perception:  B.  Russell.  Eejoinder:  C.  A.  Strong.  Some  Remarks 
on  Relativity :  R.  Ainscough. 

Smith,  Henry  Bradford:  A  First  Book  in  Logic.  New  York: 
Harper  Brothers.  1922.  viii  -f  178  pp. 

Leighton,  Joseph  Alexander :  Man  and  the  Cosmos.  An  Introduc- 
tion to  Metaphysics.  New  York :  D.  Appleton  &  Co.  1922.  xi  -f  518 
pp.  $4.50. 

Lloyd,  Alfred  H. :  Leadership  and  Progress.  Boston :  Stratford 
Company.  1922.  171  pp. 

Pieron,  Henri;  editor:  L 'Annee  Psychologique.  (1920-21) 
Paris :  Felix  Alcan.  1922.  608  pp. 

Proceedings  of  the  Aristotelian  Society,  1921-22.  Vol.  XXII, 
New  Series.  London :  Williams  &  Norgate.  1922.  241  pp.  25s. 

MacDougall,  Robert :  The  General  Problems  of  Psychology.  New 
York  University  Press.  1922.  x  +  464  pp. 


Jill  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

NOTES  AND  NEWS 

The  Rev.  James  Hastings,  D.D.,  originator  and  editor  of  the 
Dictionary  of  the  Bible,  the  Encyclopaedia  of  Religion  and  Ethics, 
and  other  important  works,  died  October  15,  1922,  at  Kings  Gate, 
Aberdeen.  The  following  is  quoted  from  the  London  Times:  "What 
may  justly  be  called  Dr.  Hastings 's  magnum  opus,  the  "Encyclopedia 
of  Religion  and  Ethics"  in  twelve  volumes,  began  to  appear  in  1908 
and  was  completed  last  year.  This  vast  undertaking  involved  the 
constant  guidance  of  an  extraordinarily  varied  company  of  scholars 
and  specialists  of  all  countries  and  religions.  Articles  came  in  all 
civilized  languages,  and  the  supervision  of  the  translators  alone  was 
a  gigantic  task.  Although  the  work  appeals  chiefly  to  scholars  and 
experts,  it  has  nevertheless  had  a  large  sale  among  the  general  public, 
whose  interest  in  religion  and  morals  is  deeper  than  is  often  sup- 
posed. Dr.  Hastings  had  already  planned  an  extra  volume  of  indices 
to  the  whole  work,  and  he  had  also  made  researches  in  the  language 
of  the  English  versions  of  the  Bible  with  a  view  to  a  systematized 
dictionary." 

Vol.  II,  No.  5  (March  2,  1905)  of  this  JOURNAL  is  out  of  print. 
The  editors  will  pay  fifty  cents  for  a  copy  of  this  number.  . 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  24  NOVEMBER  23,  1922 

THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


DR.  SCHILLER'S  ANALYSIS  OF  THE  ANALYSIS  OF  MIND 

DR.  SCHILLER'S  article  dealing  with  me  in  this  JOURNAL  (Vol. 
XIX,  No.  11)  is  a  model  of  philosophical  discussion:  the 
points  which  he  discusses  are  fundamental,  and  the  divergences  be- 
tween him  and  me  which  he  notes  concern  vital  problems.  He  and 
I  are  agreed,  I  think,  that  it  is  impossible  to  produce  logical  argu- 
ments on  either  side  of  the  questions  which  divide  us.  Philosophies 
which  differ  radically  necessarily  involve  different  logics,  and  there- 
fore can  not  be  proved  or  refuted  by  logic  without  question-begging. 
Accordingly,  the  remarks  which  I  shall  have  to  make  will  be  of  the 
nature  of  rhetoric  rather  than  logic. 

Dr.  Schiller  begins  by  deploring  my  atavistic  tendency  to  return 
to  Hume.  To  this  I  plead  guilty  at  once.  I  regard  the  whole 
romantic  movement,  beginning  with  Rousseau  and  Kant,  and  cul- 
minating in  pragmatism  and  futurism,  as  a  regrettable  aberration. 
I  should  take  ' '  back  to  the  18th  century  "  as  a  battle-cry,  if  I  could* 
entertain  any  hope  that  others  would  rally  to  it.  What  I  object  to 
about  the  intervening  period  is  summed  up  in  Lord  Tennyson's 
"  noble  "  words: 

But  like  a  man  in  wrath,  the  heart 

Stood  up  and  answered:  I  have  felt. 

I  dislike  the  heart  as  an  inspirer  of  beliefs;  I  much  prefer  the 
spleen.  I  take  comfort  in  Freud's  work,  because  it  shows  what  we 
are  to  think  of  the  heart,  which,  he  says,  makes  us  desire  the  death 
of  our  parents,  and  therefore  dream  that  they  are  dead,  with  a  hypo- 
critical sorrow  in  our  very  dreams.  The  heart  is  the  cause  of  the 
anti-rational  philosophy  that  begins  with  Kant  and  leads  up  to  the 
"will  to  believe."  The  heart  is  the  inspirer  of  atrocities  against 
negroes,  the  late  war,  and  the  starvation  of  Russia.  (See  McDou- 
gall's  Social  Psychology,  which  attributes  actions  of  this  kind  to 
"the  tender  emotion.")  People  who  believe  in  the  heart  agree  with 
Dr.  Schiller's  dislike  of  "abstract  analysis  in  search  of  the  'simple' 
and  elemental,  conducted  from  the  standpoint  of  an  extraneous  ob- 
server." Why  I  like  them  I  do  not  know,  though  probably  any 

645 


<nr,  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

"extraneous  observer"  could  tell  me.  But  I  can  suggest  reasons 
which  might  lead  other  people  to  believe  in  them. 

I  begin  with  the  question  of  the  "extraneous  observer."  For 
reasons,  some  of  which  I  have  set  forth  in  The  Analysis  of  Mind, 
I  hold  self-knowledge  to  be  very  precarious  and  deceptive.  What 
little  I  know  about  myself  I  owe  to  the  observations  of  candid 
friends.  The  greater  reliability  of  external  observation  is  shown 
by  the  usual  scientific  tests — power  of  prediction,  etc.  The  whole 
method  of  psycho-analysis  is  a  vindication  of  the  trained  outside 
observer.  Dr.  Schiller,  of  course,  is  not  advocating  old-fashioned 
introspection,  which  makes  one's  ego  an  object  and  tries  to  duplicate 
it  into  observer  and  observed.  He  is  advocating  what  he  calls 
"activist  psychology,"  according  to  which  activity  is  the  funda- 
mental thing.  Now  it  may  be  that  I  am  an  unusually  lazy  person, 
but  the  fact  is  that  I  know  nothing  of  "activity."  I  observe 
that  my  body  moves  in  various  ways,  but  so  do  other  bodies,  living 
and  dead.  I  observe  that  when  my  body  moves  there  are  certain 
sensations,  and  sometimes  before  it  moves  there  are  other  sensations 
which  may  be  called  "tension"  or  "strain."  Sometimes  also  the 
movement  is  preceded  by  images  of  it,  particularly  in  the  case  of  a 
difficult  movement,  such  as  a  high  dive.  That  is  to  say,  I  can  dis- 
cover various  correlations  of  perceptions  of  bodily  movements  with 
other  perceptions  of  bodily  states,  or  with  images,  before,  after,  or 
at  the  same  time  as,  the  perceptions  of  the  bodily  movements.  But 
I  am  utterly  at  a  loss  to  recognize  this  ' '  activity ' '  which  is  supposed 
to  be  the  very  essence  of  life.  I  am  forced  to  conclude  that  I  am 
not  really  alive. 

As  for  "abstract  analysis  in  search  of  the  'simple'  and  'ele- 
mental, '  ' '  that  is  a  more  important  matter.  To  begin  with,  ' '  simple ' ' 
must  not  be  taken  in  an  absolute  sense ;  "simpler"  would  be  a  better 
word.  Of  course,  I  should  be  glad  to  reach  the  absolutely  simple, 
but  I  do  not  believe  that  that  is  within  human  capacity.  What  I  do 
maintain  is  that,  whenever  anything  is  complex,  our  knowledge  is 
advanced  by  discovering  constituents  of  it,  even  if  these  constituents 
themselves  are  still  complex.  It  is  customary  in  philosophy  to  speak 
ill  of  "abstraction,"  and  to  use  as  laudatory  epithets  such  phrases 
as  "concrete  fulness,"  "the  richness  of  the  living  flux"  etc.,  gen- 
erally supported  by  the  opinion  of  Mephistopheles  on  the  relation  of 
theory  to  life.  For  my  part,  I  am  regretfully  compelled  to  differ 
with  Mephistopheles  on  this  point.  And  even  if  I  did  not,  theory 
is  the  business  of  philosophy,  and  if  theory  is  bad,  it  is  better  to  give 
up  being  a  philosopher.  Modern  philosophers  have  not  the  courage 
of  their  profession,  and  try  to  make  their  systems  ape  real  life 


DR.  SCHILLER'S  ANALYSIS  647 

till  they  become  indistinguishable  from  jazzing.  Meanwhile  science 
pursues  a  quite  different  course.  The  more  it  advances,  the  more 
abstract  and  analytical  it  becomes;  and  the  more  abstract  and 
analytical  it  becomes,  the  more  it  is  able  to  increase  our  knowledge 
of  the  world.  Philosophy,  to  save  its  face,  has  invented  a  theory 
that  scientific  knowledge  is  not  real  knowledge,  but  that  there  is 
an  extra  superfine  brand  of  knowledge  to  be  obtained  in  philosophy, 
not  by  observation  of  the  world,  but  by  giving  way  to  our  wishes — 
particularly  the  wish  to  think  that  we  can  know  without  taking 
trouble.  This  is  to  my  mind  a  complete  delusion.  I  do  not  believe 
that  there  is  any  way  of  obtaining  knowledge  except  the  scientific 
way.  Some  of  the  problems  with  which  philosophy  has  concerned 
itself  can  be  solved  by  scientific  methods;  others  can  not.  Those 
which  can  not  are  insoluble. 

I  do  not  doubt  that  the  difference  between  those  who  like  analysis 
and  those  who  dislike  it  is  temperamental.  I  can  not  prove  that 
analysis  is  the  right  method  except  by  using  analysis,  which  would 
beg  the  question — I  will  not  even  deny  that  the  mystics  (as  one 
may  call  the  opponents  of  analysis)  might  have  had  the  best  of  it  in 
practice.  But  in  arguing  with  a  pragmatist  it  is  permissible  to 
point  to  the  extraordinary  fruitfulness  of  science,  which  uses  anal- 
ysis, as  against  the  sterility  of  philosophy,  which  rejects  it.  Nay 
more,  as  against  such  an  opponent  it  is  permissible  to  point  out  that 
analysis  enables  us  to  produce  the  necessaries  of  life  and  defeat 
competitors — which  ought,  on  pragmatist  grounds,  to  be  the  ultimate 
test  of  truth.  I  therefore  make  no  apology  for  using  analytic  meth- 
ods. If  they  have  dropped  out  of  philosophy  since  Kant  introduced 
the  "practical  reason,"  so  much  the  worse  for  philosophy.  I 
respect  Descartes,  Leibniz,  Locke,  Berkeley,  and  Hume,  all  of  whom 
employed  the  analytic  method.  I  do  not  believe  that  Kant  or 
Hegel  or  Nietzsche  or  the  more  modern  anti-rationalists  have  con- 
tributed anything  that  deserves  to  be  remembered. 

I  pass  by  the  question  of  the  relation  of  Kant  to  Hume,  as  of 
merely  historical  interest,  remarking  only  that,  whatever  may  have 
been  Kant's  intellectual  debt  to  Hume,  the  difference  between  their 
temperaments  and  desires  was  very  great.  The  next  point  of  im- 
portance in  Dr.  Schiller's  paper  concerns  the  relations  between 
psychic  elements.  He  says  of  me:  "This  psychological  analysis  as- 
sumes that  it  can  start  with  an  indefinite  plurality  of  entities  or 
facts,  out  of  which  psychic  structures  can  be  built.  .  .  .  Russell,  for 
example,  may  sometimes  be  found  to  declare  that  his  'main  thesis' 
is  that  'all  psychic  phenomena  are  built  up  out  of  sensations  and 
images  alone.'  Actually  these  structures  do  require  (and  employ) 


648  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

a  minimum  of  mortar,  both  in  Hume  and  in  Russell.  This  is  intro- 
duced under  the  names  of  'association,'  'causality,'  'memory,'  'ex- 
pectation,' and  sundry  'relations,'  such  as  'meaning.'  But  their 
presence  and  activity  are  so  little  emphasized  that  they  are  even 
verbally  denied,  as  in  the  passage  just  quoted." 

This  passage  shows  a  misunderstanding  which  is  truly  aston- 
ishing. If  I  said  "the  walls  of  my  house  are  built  of  bricks  and 
mortar  alone,"  should  I  be  supposed  to  be  asserting  or  implying 
that  my  walls  were  indistinguishable  from  a  heap  of  separate  bricks 
and  a  puddle  of  mortar?  It  is  obvious  that  the  bricks  in  the  wall 
have  a  structure,  that  the  structure  consists  of  relations  between 
the  bricks,  that  these  relations  are  given  empirically  in  whatever 
sense  the  bricks  are  given,  and  that  the  relations  are  something 
other  than  the  materials  of  which  the  walls  are  built.  Similarly  in 
the  passage  which  Dr.  Schiller  quotes,  I  did  not  suggest  or  imply 
that  sensations  and  images  would  constitute  all  psychic  phenomena 
without  suitable  relations,  any  more  than  that  bricks  and  mortar 
would  constitute  a  house  while  they  remained  in  haphazard  heaps. 
And  so  far  from  not  emphasizing  the  relations  required,  the  discus- 
sion of  them  forms  a  large  part  of  the  book.  In  fact,  it  will  be 
seen  from  the  last  two  pages  of  the  book  that  these  relations  are 
what  I  regard  as  giving  mind  its  character,  for  I  say  that  mind 
consists  chiefly  in  number  and  complexity  of  habits,  and  habits  are 
obviously  constituted  by  relations.  I  do,  however,  most  strenuously 
deny  that  the  relations  which  I  observe,  whether  in  the  mental  or 
the  physical  world,  are  a  priori  principles  of  synthesis  in  the  Kan- 
tian sense.  When  I  look  at  a  wall,  I  perceive  parts  with  spatial  rela- 
tions; so  I  do  when  I  contemplate  a  complex  visual  image.  Rela- 
tions and  terms  are  given  together,  and  are  alike  empirical.  Not 
of  course  all  relations,  or  all  terms — some  are  inferred,  but  the  in- 
ference would  be  impossible  unless  some  were  empirical  data. 

Dr.  Schiller  continues:  "The  plurality,  which  common-sense, 
Hume,  and  Russell,  all  treat  as  a  datum,  is  not  present  in  the 
original  experience,  and  is  at  best  a  construction  resulting  from  a 
course  of  philosophic  reflection. ' '  This  statement  seems  to  me  to  be 
an  instance  of  a  very  common  fallacy  in  psychology,  namely  the 
assumption  that  nothing  is  happening  in  a  man's  mind  except  what 
he  is  aware  of.  This  assumption  is  often  supported  by  an  appeal 
to  James's  remarks  on  the  "psychologist's  fallacy,"  but  in  fact  such 
support  is  illusory.  James  argues,  very  correctly,  that  a  given 
situation  will  not  have  precisely  the  same  effect  upon  a  layman  as 
upon  a  psychologist,  because  the  psychologist  has  trained  himself 
to  a  certain  kind  of  reaction.  I  am  willing  to  believe  that,  before 


DR.  SCHILLER'S  ANALYSIS  649 

James's  time,  there  were  psychologists  who  committed  this  fallacy, 
but  since  his  time  it  is  the  opposite  fallacy  that  has  become  com- 
mon. It  is  now  constantly  assumed  that  if  a  savage,  a  baby,  or  a 
monkey  has  an  experience  which  he  or  it  does  not  discriminate  into 
related  parts,  then  the  experience  in  question  does  not  consist  of 
related  parts.  It  would  be  exactly  as  valid  to  argue  that  because 
Newton's  apple  did  not  know  it  was  falling,  therefore  it  was  not 
falling,  and  the  theory  of  gravitation  may  be  dismissed  as  an  ex- 
ample of  the  "psychologist's  fallacy." 

The  notion  that  a  savage  or  an  animal  is  the  best  judge  as  to 
the  general  nature  of  his  own  mental  processes  is  not  held  in  any 
other  context.  Even  in  civilized  and  highly  educated  people,  psy- 
cho-analysts detect  all  kinds  of  processes  of  which  they  are  uncon- 
scious. Nevertheless,  when  a  savage  shows  that  he  is  muddle- 
headed  as  to  the  muddle  in  his  head,  it  is  assumed  that  we  ought 
to  learn  to  be  equally  muddle-headed,  and  that  no  clear  account 
of  his  muddle  is  possible.  This  favoritism  seems  to  indicate  a 
bias  in  favor  of  muddle.  For  my  part,  I  regard  muddle  as  a 
phenomenon  like  another.  I  see  no  more  reason  to  be  muddled  in 
investigating  a  muddle  than  to  be  muddled  in  investigating  any- 
thing else.  One  might  as  well  maintain  that  a  theory  of  wind 
ought  to  blow  one  away,  or  that  a  theory  of  undulation  ought  to 
make  one  seasick.  Savages  are  muddled  as  to  what  is  going  on, 
whether  inside  them  or  outside  them,  and  their  account  is  not  to  be 
accepted.  Therefore,  when  Dr.  Schiller  says  "the  plurality  .  .  . 
is  not  present  in  the  original  experience,"  he  is  misled  by  the 
ambiguity  of  the  word  "experience."  I  should  say:  "The  plural- 
ity is  present  in  the  original  occurrence,  but  is  not  experienced." 
I  should  add  that,  however  sophisticated  we  become,  most  of  what 
happens  to  us  is  not  experienced  by  us;  in  regard  to  most  of  the 
occurrences  of  our  lives,  we  are  as  unconscious  as  Newton's  apple. 

The  next  point  to  be  considered  concerns  Dr.  Schiller's  state- 
ment that  my  "method  is  not  concerned  with  the  actual  course  of 
mental  development,  but  with  an  ideal  description  of  its  products. 
It  takes  an  adult  mind  and  rearranges  its  contents  in  a  systematic 
and  esthetically  pleasing  order. ' '  This  statement  seems  to  me  partly 
true  and  partly  false.  I  deny  that  I  am  not  concerned  with  the 
actual  course  of  mental  development,  and  also  that  I  take  an  adult 
mind  in  the  sense  intended.  I  admit  that  I  rearrange  the  contents 
in  a  systematic  and  esthetically  [or  logically]  pleasing  order,  but 
then  that  is  the  very  business  of  science.  As  for  taking  an  adult 
mind,  I  begin  with  Thorndike's  animals  in  cages,  which  may  have 
been  adult  animals,  but  were  not  "adult  minds"  in  the  sense  re- 


650  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

quired  for  Dr.  Schiller's  point.  I  have  tried  throughout  to  take 
account  of  whatever  can  be  learnt  about  infant  and  animal  psy- 
chology. It  is  partly  for  this  reason  that  I  have  been  concerned  to 
praise  behaviorism,  which  has  adopted  the  only  method  by  which 
infant  and  animal  psychology  can  be  made  scientific.  But  when  I 
had  (as  I  thought)  exhausted,  what  could  be  learnt  by  behaviorist 
methods,  and  felt  obliged  to  call  in  the  aid  of  introspection,  I  was 
compelled  to  have  recourse  to  the  adult  mind,  because  unfortunately 
I  am  adult.  Dr.  Schiller  appears  to  possess  some  mysterious 
method,  other  than  behaviorism,  by  which  he  can  ascertain  what 
goes  on  in  the  minds  of  infants  and  animals,  and  he  implies  that  it 
is  more  like  what  goes  on  in  his  mind  than  like  what  goes  on  in 
mine.  As  for  that,  I  must  take  his  word  for  it.  But  even  then  I 
am  not  obliged  to  admit  that  they  have  true  beliefs  as  to  what  goes 
on  in  their  own  minds. 

What  Dr.  Schiller  is  really  objecting  to  is,  I  suppose,  that  my 
method  is  not  historical  or  evolutionary.  I  have,  it  is  true,  dis- 
cussed the  process  of  learning  somewhat  fully,  but  I  am  equally 
interested  in  processes  which  are  not  progressive.  I  think  the  inter- 
est in  development  which  came  in  with  evolution  is  a  barrier  to  the 
elementary  understanding  of  the  simpler  facts  upon  which  any 
solid  science  must  be  built.  Laplace's  Mecanique  Celeste  presup- 
posed Galileo,  Kepler,  and  Newton,  who  treated  the  solar  system 
as  a  stable  adult.  Similarly  there  will  be  no  beginning  of  a  genu- 
ine science  of  psychology  so  long  as  people  are  obsessed  by  such 
complex  facts  as  growth  and  progress.  I  know  it  is  customary  to 
treat  life  as  essentially  progressive.  But  this  seems  to  be  a  sheer 
mistake.  If  a  census  could  be  taken  of  all  the  organisms  now  liv- 
ing, I  have  no  doubt  that  an  immense  majority  would  be  found  to 
be  unicellular,  and  to  have  made  no  appreciable  progress  since  the 
origin  of  life.  And  to  the  remainder,  decay  is  quite  as  natural  as 
growth.  Yet  Dr.  Schiller  does  not  reproach  me  with  having  paid 
too  little  attention  to  senility. 

Some  of  Dr.  Schiller's  criticisms  are  quite  beyond  my  compre- 
hension. He  says,  as  an  objection  to  me,  "a  biologically  possible 
analysis  can  not  start  from  anything  less  than  the  whole  process 
involved  in  an  act,  viz.,  a  response  to  stimulation  which  is  salutary, 
or  harmful,  and  is  selected  accordingly."  Who  would  suppose, 
reading  this,  that  this  is  the  very  thing  I  do  start  from?  It  is  the 
same  thing  that  I  have  called  a  "behavior-cycle,"  and  I  have  put 
it  at  the  beginning,  as  being  characteristic  of  living  organisms.  I 
observe,  however,  (a)  that  a  process  of  this  kind  is  complex,  and 
therefore  susceptible  of  logical  analysis;  (6)  that  when  we  come 


CRITICAL  REALISM  651 

to  the  more  elaborate  processes  which  we  are  aware  of  carrying 
out,  we  find  need  of  elements  which  it  does  not  seem  necessary  to 
assume  in  order  to  account  for  the  responses  of  an  amoeba;  (c)  that 
"response  to  stimulation,"  as  we  ourselves  experience  it,  often  in- 
volves something  that  may  be  called,  in  some  sense,  awareness  of 
the  stimulus,  and  thus  lands  us  with  the  problem  of  perception  and 
even  of  memory. 

I  have  only  one  more  subject  to  discuss,  namely  the  subject.  It 
is  surprising  to  find  Dr.  Schiller  sticking  up  for  the  old-fashioned 
soul,  and  quoting  with  disapproval  the  remarks  about  the  ghost  of 
the  subject,  which  once  was  the  full-blooded  soul,  which  I  adapted 
from  William  James.1  He  does  not  apparently  notice  that  the  re- 
mark to  which  he  objects  is  a  paraphrase  of  James's,  but  his  at- 
titude shows  that  he  is  less  in  agreement  with  James  than  is  com- 
monly supposed.  The  background  of  their  thoughts  is  very  dif- 
ferent. James's  mind  was  a  battle-ground  of  medical  materialism 
and  the  mysticism  suggested  by  Swedenborg.  His  learned  self  was 
scientific  and  his  emotional  self  cosmic;  neither  led  him  to  attach 
great  value  to  the  ego.  On  the  other  hand,  Dr.  Schiller's  learned 
self  is  primarily  hellenic.  He  is  fond  of  claiming  affinity  with 
Protagoras,  who  would  hardly  have  suited  James.  Idealism  is  to 
him  what  James  called  a  ' '  live  option " ;  at  one  time  he  collaborated 
in  a  work  called  Personal  Idealism.  It  seems  to  follow  that  the 
parts  of  James's  work  with  which  I  sympathize  most  are  those  with 
which  he  sympathizes  least.  This  case  of  the  soul  is  one  of  them. 
On  this  question  I  can  safely  leave  the  argument  to  James's  Ameri- 
can successors,  from  whom  I  have  learnt  many  of  the  doctrines 
advocated  in  The  Analysis  of  Mind. 

BEBTEAND  RUSSELL. 

LONDON. 

CRITICAL  REALISM  AND  THE  EXTERNAL  WORLD  l 

ESSAYS  in  Critical  Realism  is  offered  as  a  new  solution  of  an 
old  epistemological  problem.  Its  authors,  a  group  of  phi- 
losophers who  differ  on  many  important  metaphysical  points,  have 
here  united  upon  certain  matters  connected  with  a  theory  of  knowl- 
edge. This  theory  of  knowledge,  it  is  hoped,  will  enable  us  all  to 
satisfy  our  natural  cravings  to  be  realists.  "An  honest  man  .  .  . 
is  a  realist  at  heart. "  2  It  is  maintained  that,  if  non-realistic  phi- 

i  See  the  quotation  from  him  in  Analysis  of  Mind,  p.  22. 

1  Read  at  the  meeting  of  the  Western  Division  of  the  American  Philosoph- 
ical Association,  at  Lincoln,  April  14,  1922. 

2  P.  184  (Mr.  Santayana).     Unless  otherwise  stated  the  references  are  to 
Essays  in  Critical  Bealism.    The  name  of  the  author  quoted  will  in  each  case 
be  noted. 


652  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

losophies  have  dominated  the  thinking  of  many  persons  during  the 
last  century,  the  trouble  has  been  that  realism  has  not  known  how 
properly  to  present  its  claim.  The  central  issue  of  the  new  co- 
operative volume  is  our  ability  to  know  the  external  world.  Hence 
by  its  success  in  meeting  this  issue,  critical  realism  must  primarily 
be  judged.  That  the  volume  has  many  good  features  and  some  at- 
tractive sections,  no  fair  critic  could  deny.  The  entire  volume 
emphasizes  ably  the  ideal  reference  in  all  thinking,  the  operation- 
of  the  mind  in  terms  of  logical  essences  which  can  not  be  explained 
as  sensational  or  imaginal.  Without  such  essences  or  meanings 
reflection  could  not  go  on.  Historically,  most  realisms  have  wholly 
neglected  these  essences,  and  have  thus  in  this  respect  been  greatly 
improved  upon  and  perhaps  superseded  by  critical  realism.  But 
it  is  with  the  argument  for  an  external  world  that  critical  realism 
aims  first  of  all  to  deal.  The  importance  and  the  value  of  the 
volume  depend  fundamentally  upon  the  soundness  of  this  argu- 
ment. 

The  term  critical  realism  was  chosen  with  a  definite  meaning 
in  mind.  The  new  philosophy  is  a  realism  because  it  believes  we 
can  know  extra-mental  realities;  it  is  critical  because  it  distin- 
guishes these  objects  from  the  immediate  content  of  the  mind.  A 
clear  statement  of  the  position  of  critical  realism  is  given  in  the 
following  passage:  "Knowledge  is  just  the  insight  into  the  nature 
of  the  object  that  is  made  possible  by  the  contents  which  reflect  it 
in  consciousness."8  The  external  objects  "assist  in  the  rise  in  the 
organism  of  subjective  data  which  are  the  raw  material  of  knowl- 
edge, ' '  *  but  yet  can  themselves  ' '  be  known  only  in  terms  of  the 
data  which  they  control  within  us. ' ' 5  Unless  external  objects  were 
really  existent,  the  psychical  content  would  not  arise  in  the  mind. 
Unless  psychical  content  were  present  to  mind,  we  would  not  know 
objects.  Yet  we  know  the  external  objects,  not  the  psychical  states, 
even  though  we  know  those  objects  through  the  instrumentality  of 
the  psychical  states.  The  subjective  content  is  the  terminus  a  quo, 
not  the  terminus  ad  quern,  of  knowledge. 

This  position  of  the  critical  realists  is  subject  to  misunderstand- 
ing by  a  careless  reader ;  for  a  rather  common  supposition  has  been 
that  the  object  immediately  present  to  consciousness  must  also  be 
the  object  known.  Not  so,  however,  with  the  critical  realists.  "What 
we  perceive,  conceive,  remember,  think  of,  is  the  outer  object  it- 
self, '"an  object  independent  of  the  processes  of  knowledge  and  of 

•  P.  200  (Mr.  Sellars). 
4  P.  192  (Mr.  SeUart). 

•  P.  217  (Mr.  Sellara). 

•  P.  4  (Mr.  Drake). 


CRITICAL  REALISM  653 

the  effects  which  it  may  chance  to  produce  in  consciousness.  Yet 
we  never  come  into  contact  with  that  object  directly.  "We  have 
no  power  of  penetrating  to  the  object  itself  and  intuiting  it  im- 
mediately, ' ' 7  but  have  immediately  present  to  us  only  subjective 
content.  "The  knower  is  confined  to  the  datum,  and  can  never 
literally  inspect  the  existent  which  he  affirms  and  claims  to  know."  8 
In  other  words  the  object  of  perception  and  the  content  of  percep- 
tion are  two  separate  things,  the  former  being  objective  and  the 
latter  subjective ;  and  though  the  latter  is  caused  by  the  former  and 
the  former  is  known  by  means  of  the  latter,  "their  existence  is 
quite  distinct  and  their  conditions  entirely  different. " 9  As  the 
position  is  beautifully  summed  up  in  one  passage:  "The  objects 
themselves,  i.e.,  those  bits  of  existence,  do  not  get  within  our  con- 
sciousness. Their  existence  is  their  own  affair,  private,  incommuni- 
cable. One  existent  (my  organism,  or  mind)  can  not  go  out  beyond 
itself  literally,  and  include  another  existent;  between  us  all,  ex- 
istentially  speaking,  is  'the  unplumb'd,  salt,  estranging  sea.'"10 

Thus  incompletely  stated,  critical  realism  recalls  Locke's  Essay. 
In  spite  of  the  disregard  which  some  of  the  critical  realists  feel  for 
their  seventeenth-century  ancestor,  there  are  strong  resemblances. 
Yet  there  are  important  differences  too,  which  call  for  notice. 
Sometimes,  to  be  sure,  Locke  gave  up  all  hope  of  knowing  the  real, 
outer  object;  he  regarded  it  almost  as  unknowable  as  Kant  later 
regarded  his  Ding  an  sick,  and  confined  human  knowledge  to  rela- 
tions between  the  ideas  or  bits  of  subjective  content.  This  the 
critical  realists  never  do.  But  at  other  times  Locke,  just  as  much 
as  the  critical  realists,  regarded  the  ideas,  not  as  the  objects  to  which 
knowledge  was  directed,  but  as  the  means  by  which  knowledge  was 
mediated  of  real,  outer,  external  objects.  He  then  speaks  of  knowl- 
edge of  "real  existence."  And  with  great  emphasis  he  says:  "If 
our  knowledge  of  our  ideas  terminate  in  them,  and  reach  no  farther, 
where  there  is  something  farther  intended,  our  most  serious  thought 
will  be  of  little  more  use  than  the  reveries  of  a  crazy  brain ;  and  the 
truths  built  thereon  of  no  more  weight  than  the  discourses  of  a 
man  who  sees  things  clearly  in  a  dream,  and  with  great  assurance 
utters  them. ' ' "  Yet  even  with  this  second  and  more  realistic 
strain  in  Locke,  the  critical  realists  believe  themselves  not  in  agree- 
ment. In  many  passages  surely,  Locke,  no  more  than  the  critical 
realists,  took  the  immediate  content  of  mind  as  the  objects  of  knowl- 

T  P.  225  (Mr.  Strong). 

«  P.  203  (Mr.  Sellars). 

»  P.  165  (Mr.  Santayana). 

10  p.  24  (Mr.  Drake). 

"  Locke:  Essay  Concerning  the  Human  Understanding,  Bk  IV,  chap.  4,  $.  2. 


(i.-,l  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

edge.  But  it  is  true  that  Locke  did  not  distinguish,  and  that  the 
critical  realists  do  distinguish,  between  mental  contents  and  data. 
And  it  is  because  of  Locke's  failure  to  take  the  data,  the  logical  es- 
sences, into  account,  that  he  is  deemed  unsatisfactory  and  out- 
worn. The  critical  realists  contend  that  along  with  the  subjective 
content  there  also  are  disclosed  certain  essences,  which  can  not  be 
taken  as  giving  merely  the  whatness  of  the  subjective  content,  but 
which  do  give  the  whatness  of  the  external  objects  (except  where 
the  mind  is  in  error).  Hence  it  is  maintained  that  through  the 
essences  we  can  bridge  the  estranging  sea  and  can  know  the  world 
as  it  really  is  constituted  in  itself.  Even  if  we  do  not  have  objects 
existentially  present  within  consciousness,  we  reach  those  objects 
by  "a  logical,  essential,  virtual  grasp"  of  the  mind.12  We  are 
thus  enabled  to  affirm  objects. 

The  central  issue  in  the  new  theory  of  knowledge  given  by  the 
critical  realists  boils  down  to  the  question  whether  the  recognition 
of  the  data  or  essences  enables  us  to  know  external  objects,  whether 
the  critical  realists  are  better  off  than  Locke  or  any  one  who  tried 
to  infer  external  objects  from  the  subjective  content  alone.  If  the 
historical  types  of  realism  upon  a  foundation  of  epistemological 
dualism  can  not  bridge  the  gap  between  mind  and  object,  what  as- 
sistance can  be  derived  from  the  affirmation  of  essences?  The  con- 
tention of  the  present  paper  is  that  the  critical  realists  face  exactly 
the  same  difficulty  as  that  which  they  confess  was  present  in  older 
realisms.  Even  if  the  critical  realists  give  a  better  analysis  of 
what  thinking  is,  they  are  no  whit  better  off  in  getting  from  the 
thinking  mind  to  the  external  world. 

The  premises  of  critical  realism  rule  out  the  possibility  of 
knowledge  in  the  sense  in  which  they  desire  it.  Knowledge  is  "true 
opinion  with  reason";  and  "an  opinion  is  true  if  what  it  is  talking 
about  is  constituted  as  the  opinion  asserts  it  to  be  constituted."18 
Or,  in  other  words,  knowledge  is  a  matter  of  "correspondence  or 
conformity  of  the  knowledge-content  with  the  selected  object."14 
But  if  we  grant  the  premises  of  critical  realism,  how  can  we  ever 
be  sure  that  our  opinions  are  true?  How  can  we  hence  have  knowl- 
edge! If  real  objects  are  not  present  directly  to  the  mind,  if  the 
mind  has  "no  power  of  penetrating  to  the  object  itself,"  how  can 
we  be  sure  that  the  propositions  in  which  we  express  our  opinions 
conform  to  objects  beyond?  What  test  is  there  for  truth?  .One 

"P.  28  (Mr.  Drake). 

"Pp.  98,  99  (Mr.  Pratt).    Quoted  by  Mr.  Pratt  from  Mr.  Santayana. 

n  Sellars:  Evolutionary  Naturalism,  p.  55.  Though  quoted  from  Mr. 
Sellars'a  last  book  rather  than  from  the  cooperative  volume,  it  may  fairly  be 
assumed  that  he  speaks  for  the  rest  of  the  critical  realists  on  this  point. 


CRITICAL  REALISM  655 

might  suppose,  were  it  not  for  Mr.  Lovejoy's  excessive  fury  with 
pragmatism,  that  the  predicament  of  the  critical  realists  would 
make  them  glad  to  accept  workability  as  an  alternative  for  the  older 
meaning  of  truth ;  yet  the  critical  realists  all  agree  in  rejecting  the 
pragmatic  point  of  view.  By  their  own  theory  of  the  un-get-at- 
ableness  of  objects,  the  critical  realists  have  eliminated  any  chance 
of  proving  that  the  essences  we  have  in  mind  are  the  correct  what- 
ness  of  the  external  objects.  Truth  being  conformity  of  an  essence 
to  an  object  we  can  by  hypothesis  never  reach,  knowledge  is  impos- 
sible. 

The  fault  with  critical  realism  is  not  that  it  does  not  allow  for 
the  occurrence  of  error,  but  that  it  does  not  permit  us  to  know 
when  we  have  the  truth  and  when  we  are  in  error.  It  may  well  be 
that  the  data  or  essences  ' '  are  irresistibly  taken  to  be  the  characters 
of  the  existents  perceived,  or  otherwise  known. " 15  If  this  were 
granted,  it  could  still  be  asked  how  we  know  when  they  are  cor- 
rectly so  taken  and  when  incorrectly.  It  is  not  enough  to  confess 
that  "there  is  always  a  bare  possibility  of  illusion  or  hallucina- 
tion " ; 16  rather  there  is  no  possibility  of  distinguishing  between 
hallucination  and  veridical  perception  at  all.  We  are  told  that 
"experience  indicates  an  actual,  causally  based  agreement  between 
the  physical  existent  and  the  content  of  perception."17  But  how 
can  experience  of  the  subjective  sort  postulated  by  the  critical 
realists  ever  indicate  whether  we  are  justified  in  predicating  es- 
sences of  external  objects?  How  can  we  say  that  agreement  is  in- 
dicated if  one  of  the  things  between  which  agreement  is  asserted 
is  inaccessible?  We  are  told  that  in  dealing  with  subjective  con- 
tent and  external  object  "the  tendency  of  the  realist  is  to  reply 
that  the  similarity  is  great,  and  may  even  rise  to  identity  of  es- 
sence."18 But  what  difference  would  truth  and  error  have  to  us 
if  we  could  not  tell  which  was  which,  if  we  could  not  tell  when 
there  is  identity  and  when  not?  It  is  maintained  that  the  mind 
may  "rest  directly  on  the  object"  in  cases  of  knowledge  since  the 
essence  is  universal  and  so  can  be  both  in  the  mind  and  in  the  ob- 
ject, and  that  only  in  cases  of  error  is  there  dualism  between  the 
essence  in  the  mind  and  the  essence  of  the  object.19  But  how  can 
we  know  when  our  minds  are  resting  on  objects,  since  the  objects 
are  not  present  to  the  mind  except  in  so  far  as  their  essence  is  pres- 
ent? The  essence  is  present  to  the  mind  in  case  of  error  just  as 

is  p.  5  (Mr.  Drake). 

ie  P.  32  (Mr.  Drake). 

«P.  202  (Mr.  Sellars). 

is  P.  165  (Mr.  Santayana). 

«P.  202  (Mr.  Sellars). 


(,.-,<i  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

clearly  as  in  the  case  of  true  opinion;  and  determination  of  truth 
and  error,  if  not  definition  of  their  abstract  meaning,  is  impossible 
to  one  shut  up  to  the  content  of  his  own  mind.  Critical  realism, 
though  not  denying  the  possibility  of  true  opinion  and  also  of 
error,  does  prevent  us  from  distinguishing  between  them  in  every 
case  except  where  for  some  special  purpose  we  choose  to  make  the 
subjective  content  or  the  essences  themselves  the  object  of  our  in- 
quiries. Those  essences  would  give  us  true  opinion  which  contain 
or  conform  to  the  "structure,  position,  and  changes"  of  objects;20 
but  essences  which  give  us  wrong  opinions  about  the  structure, 
position,  and  changes  of  objects  might  often  be  accepted  as  irresist- 
ibly as  those  which  give  us  true  opinions  thereof.  To  a  critical 
realist  a  satisfactory  essence  would  have  to  be  one  which  was  in- 
ternally useful,  not  one  which  was  objectively  true. 

One  should  not  be  confused,  and  some  of  the  critical  realists 
seem  to  be  confused,  by  the  discovery  that  in  perception  or  any 
other  consciousness  we  affirm  an  object.  Affirmation  does  not  con- 
stitute proof.  We  may  affirm  objects  constantly  without  proving 
a  single  one  to  be  as  we  affirm  it,  or  even  to  be  in  existence  at  all. 
One  of  the  critical  realists  draws  a  distinction  between  inferring 
an  object  and  affirming  an  object,  and  maintains  that  we  do  not 
infer,  but  only  affirm.21  That  is  the  very  trouble.  There  is  no 
basis  for  inference, — or  rather  there  is  no  check  upon  inference; 
there  is  only  affirmation,  made  earnestly,  upheld  enthusiastically, 
followed  persistently.  But  it  is  sheer  affirmation.  It  is  sheer  dog- 
matism. It  is  an  exhibition  of  the  sort  of  enthusiasm  which  Locke 
so  effectively  opposed  in  his  Essay,  Book  IV,  chapter  19,  a  chapter 
from  which  we  may  learn  much  still.  After  saying  that  there  are 
"two  elements  in  perception,  the  affirmation  of  a  co-real  and  the 
assigned  set  of  characters  or  aspects,"  it  is  concluded  that  "the 
content  is  intuited,  the  object  is  reacted  to  and  affirmed."22  The 
last  phrase  is  ambiguous.  It  should  mean  just  what  the  first  phrase 
meant,  namely  that  there  is  an  affirmation  of  an  object.  It  implies 
to  a  hasty  reader  that  it  has  been  found  that  there  is  an  object 
really  there  which  is  reacted  to  and  affirmed.  Such  a  conclusion 
would  doubtless  be  welcome,  but  can  not  be  derived  from  the  prem- 
ises. Yet  it  seems  that  the  distinction  between  these  two  mean- 
ings is  not  understood  in  the  essay  from  which  the  quotation  is 
made.  Others  of  the  critical  realists  do  take  account  of  this  distinc- 
tion, with  the  result  that  they  are  much  readier  to  grant  the  dan- 
ger of  total  skepticism.  It  is  even  acknowledged  that  the  external 

w  p.  200  (Mr.  Sellers). 

«  P.  195  (Mr.  Sellars). 

"P.  196  (Mr.  Sellars). 


CRITICAL  REALISM  657 

objects  may  be  the  physical  entities  of  the  physicist,  the  other 
centers  of  consciousness  of  the  panpsychist,  or  some  such  reality 
as  might  be  defined  by  an  ontological  idealist.23  But  most  of  the 
critical  realists  have  not  the  intellectual  bravery  to  confess  that 
there  may  be  no  external  objects  at  all.  Not  simply  can  not  we 
reach  the  external  objects  to  check  up  on  our  opinions  as  to  their 
nature,  but  we  can  not  even  get  outside  the  mind  to  find  if  there 
are  objects  there.  Perhaps  nothing  exists  beyond  the  subjective 
contents  and  the  essences.  We  may  be  affirming  essences  in  an 
ontological  vacuum. 

The  problem  of  knowledge  raises  the  question  of  transcendence 
which  is  occasionally  treated,  but  in  different  ways,  by  the  different 
critical  realists.  Contradictions  within  critical  realism  here  emerge 
according  to  the  willingness  of  the  various  authors  to  grant  the  full 
implications  of  their  premises.  On  the  one  hand  it  is  said :  ' '  Knowl- 
edge of  the  existents  affirmed  requires  no  more  transcendence  than 
does  this  affirmation."!24  In  one  sense  this  proposition  is  true  but 
altogether  useless  to  a  consistent  critical  realist;  in  another  sense 
it  would  be  a  valuable  aid  but  is  false.  The  former  sense  would  be 
that  to  know  an  existent  (or  external  object)  no  further  transcen- 
dence is  required  than  is  involved  in  checking  up,  or  following 
through  to  its  destination,  the  affirmation  of  the  existent.  The 
latter  sense  would  be  that  to  know  an  existent  no  further  transcen- 
dence is  required  than  to  affirm  it.  Those  two  senses  of  the  original 
proposition  have  been  repeatedly  confused  in  some  essays  of  the 
volume.  The  former  sense  of  the  proposition,  though  true,  would 
not  do  away  with  the  necessity  of  getting  beyond  subjective  con- 
tents and  the  affirmation  of  an  essence  to  the  external  world,  a 
necessity  which  runs  counter  to  the  premises  of  critical  realism. 
The  latter  sense  of  the  proposition,  though  it  would  enable  us  to 
prove  whatever  we  wanted  by  affirming  it,  is  false  in  identifying 
proof  with  convinced  and  obstinate  affirmation.  On  the  other  hand 
it  is  said:  "Minds  have  this  characteristic  of  meaning  more  than 
they  directly  experience.  .  .  .  Hence  the  critical  realist  simply  writes 
down  transcendence  as  one  of  the  facts  of  the  world,  just  as  the 
physicist  writes  down  X-rays  as  a  special  sort  of  fact."25  Here 
it  is  correctly  realized  that,  if  we  are  to  have  knowledge  instead 
of  opinions  which  are  not  checked  up,  we  must  have  transcendence. 

23  P.  109  (Mr.  Pratt).  Since  Mr.  Pratt  comes  to  this  conclusion,  one 
wonders  why  he  speaks  so  pityingly  of  der  gute  Berkeley  and  "the  weakness  of 
Berkeley's  subjectivism,"  p.  87.  Why  are  not  ideas  in  the  mind  of  God  as 
adequate  an  external  world  as  anything  else! 

2*  P.  212  (Mr.  Sellars). 

'25  p.  99  (Mr.  Pratt). 


r,.-,s  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

But  on  the  premises  of  critical  realism  which  exclude  the  possibil- 
ity of  penetrating  to  the  real  objects,  should  it  not  be  frankly  con- 
fessed that  knowledge  is  impossible  T 28  Critical  realism  can  not 
lead  to  any  other  outcome  if  it  retains  its  view  that  objects  are  in- 
accessible, unless  it  should  decide  that  knowledge  is  what  one  de- 
termines to  believe  in  the  absence  of  all  proof  on  the  basis  of  some 
deep-seated  prejudice  or  what  one  finds  convenient  to  accept  on  the 
basis  that  it  leads  to  happy  issue.  In  perhaps  the  most  illuminat- 
ing passage  in  the  collection  of  essays,  Mr.  Santayana  shows  that 
the  validity  of  knowledge  requires  that  we  regard  it  as  transitive 
and  relevant."  But  it  does  no  good  to  insist  on  transitivity  and 
then  to  deny  the  possibility  of  getting  to  the  object  with  reference 
to  which  knowledge  is  relevant. 

The  validity  of  this  critique  of  critical  realism  is  even  more  ap- 
parent when  the  illustrations  are  examined  in  which  the  existence 
of  external  objects  is  supposed  to  be  established.  Space  does  not 
permit  a  detailed  examination  here  of  more  than  one  typical  case. 
It  is  said  that  we  must  believe  in  external  objects  because  we  can 
perceive  another  individual  perceiving  an  object,  we  can  see  "the 
focusing  of  the  eyes,  the  tension  of  the  head,  the  directive  set  of 
the  whole  body,  all  leading  usually  to  behaviour  toward  the  ob- 
ject. "  "  Do  the  premises  of  the  critical  realism  permit  us  to  say 
that  we  see  these  facts?  On  the  basis  of  a  philosophy  which  did 
not  make  the  immediate  content  of  perception  "subjective,"  such 
an  inference  of  another  object  would  be  justifiable.29  But  a  critical 
realist  could  say  only  that  what  he  calls  the  other  individual  and 
his  adjustments  are  certain  subjective  content  and  certain  essences 
in  his  mind.  He  should  not  assume  the  objective  reality  of  the 
other  individual's  body  in  order  through  it  to  prove  the  objective 
reality  of  the  object  towards  which  the  other  individual  is  reacting. 
He  can  be  sure  only  that  he  has  certain  subjective  contents  and 
thinks  of  certain  essences,  and  nothing  more.  He  has  no  check  on 
the  truth  of  the  essences  until  he  gets  into  contact  with  an  external 
object;  and  he  can  not  get  into  contact  with  an  external  object 
until  he  has  some  check  on  the  truth  of  the  essences.  He  must, 

2«  In  Evolutionary  Naturalism,  p.  49,  Mr.  Sellars  defines  knowledge  as  "a 
claim  and  content  within  experience  concerning  existences,  outside  of  experience, 
mentally  selected  as  objects."  It  is  amazing  that  this  definition  can  be  ser- 
iously put  forward  in  a  book  which  operates  on  the  basis  of  critical  realism. 

27  P.  68  (Mr.  Santayana). 

"P.  196  (Mr.  Sellars). 

*»  I  personally  regard  such  an  inference  as  justifiable  on  the  basis  of  the 
theory  explained  in  my  article  in  this  JOURNAL,  March  30,  1922,  Vol.  XIX,  No. 
7,  pp.  169  ff. 


CRITICAL  REALISM  659 

therefore,  either  confess  to  arguing  in  a  circle  or  give  up  any  claim 
to  knowledge  of  a  world  without  himself.30 

The  critical  realists  do  not  all  affirm  the  external  world  with 
the  same  assurance.  The  most  confident  of  the  group  is  undoubt- 
edly Mr.  Sellars.  He  objects  to  Lockian  realism  because  it  teaches 
that  "we  first  know  our  ideas  as  objects  and  then  postulate  physi- 
cal realities. " 31  He  asserts  against  Locke  that  we  know  physical 
realities  "from  the  first."  The  contention  is  plausible  but  hides  a 
serious  confusion.  What  is  meant  by  knowing  physical  objects 
from  the  first?  If  it  means  that  from  the  beginning  of  our  experi- 
ence we  have  subjective  contents  and  essences  which  lead  us  to  af- 
firm external  objects,  there  is  nothing  inconsistent  with  the  premises 
of  critical  realism.  But  neither  is  there  anything  to  prove  physical 
objects  to  be  really  there :  the  affirmations  may  all  be  mistaken.  If, 
however,  the  phrase  means  that  we  have  greater  assurance  of  the 
existence  of  physical  objects  than  of  subjective  contents,  we  would 
have  a  sound  basis  for  realism  and  no  need  for  an  elaborate  proof 
of  the  external  world.  But  this  would  be  equivalent  to  maintain- 
ing direct  contact  of  minds  with  external  objects  and  hence  to 
giving  up  critical  realism.  The  plausibility  of  the  passage  about 
knowing  physical  objects  from  the  first  is  derived  from  a  confusion 
between  the  first  and  second  meanings  of  the  phrase.  Locke  could 
say  that  we  know  external  objects  from  the  first  in  exactly  the  same 
sense  in  which  Mr.  Sellars'  premises  would  permit  him  to  say  it; 
namely,  that  from  the  beginning  of  experience  we  have  such  mental 
contents  that  we  come  to  suppose  a  real  and  objective  world.  Even 
if  the  addition  of  essences  to  subjective  contents  is  taken  to  improve 
upon  Locke's  account  of  the  contents  of  consciousness,  it  in  no  way 
alters  the  nature  of  the  jump  from  mind  to  object. 

Others  of  the  critical  realists  realize  better  than  Mr.  Sellars  the 
difficulty  here.  It  is  said  that  the  existence  of  an  external  world 
is  a  matter  of  an  as  if,  and  consolation  is  found  in  the  fact  that 
critical  realism  is  no  worse  off  than  subjectivism  which  believes  in 
other  minds.32  Only  two  of  the  authors  in  the  volume  give  evidence 
of  following  their  premises  to  the  logical  conclusion.  Mr.  Pratt 
confesses  that  on  the  premises  of  critical  realism  "the  ultimate  na- 
ture of  reality  in  itself  may  be  very  difficult,  or  even  impossible,  to 
discover, ' ' 33  though  he  none  the  less  proceeds  to  deprecate  agnos- 
ticism in  his  closing  pages.  Mr.  Santayana  goes  in  thoroughness 

so  Cf.  also  pp.  22-24,  29,  169-170,  et  passim.  Cf.  further  Sellars:  Evoli*- 
tionary  Naturalism,  pp.  30,  32,  40. 

si  P.  193  (Mr.  Sellars). 

32  p.  6  (Mr.  Drake). 

33  p.  104  (Mr.  Pratt). 


OiiO  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

beyond  Mr.  Pratt.  He  grants  that  the  subjective  content  "might 
have  arisen  without  any  occasion,  as  idealists  believe  is  actually  the 
case, ' '  '*  and  reduces  the  passage  from  the  essence  in  thought  to 
the  existing  object  to  a  moral  basis,  "the  leap  of  faith  and  ac- 
tion,"85 a  phrase  strangely  reminiscent  of  Kant's  practical  reason. 
The  consistent  logic  of  the  premise  that  we  intuit  only  subjective 
contents  thus  proves  to  be  that  realism  is  possible  to  those  who  want 
to  assume  it.  But  so  is  ontological  idealism  or  any  other  meta- 
physics. So  even  is  skepticism.  Denial  of  all  external  reality 
would  be  no  more  of  a  hazard  of  faith  than  affirmation  of  an  ex- 
ternal reality.  Perhaps  we  are  ' '  realists  at  heart. ' '  ••  But  it  would 
seem  to  be  more  honest  to  confess  that  we  had  no  valid  reason  for 
believing  what  we  want  to  profess.  Realism  of  the  "critical"  type 
thus  proves  to  be  a  matter  of  preference,  of  personal  prejudice  or 
choice,  not  of  the  logic  of  the  premises.87 

Caesar  had  his  Brutus,  Charles  the  First  his  Cromwell,  and  Locke 
his  Hume.  The  critical  realists  should  have  gone  on  more  often 
from  their  Locke  to  their  Hume,  in  order  better  to  appreciate  the 
force  of  Hume's  disintegrating  criticism.  Any  one  could  apply  to 
critical  realism  the  epistemological  reflection  which  Hume  brought 
to  bear  on  the  Lockian  tradition  which  assumed  that  the  immediate 
content  of  the  mind  is  "subjective."  He  wrote:  "As  to  those  im- 
pressions which  arise  from  the  senses,  their  ultimate  cause  is,  in 
my  opinion,  perfectly  inexplicable  by  human  reason,  and  'twill 
always  be  impossible  to  decide  with  certainty,  whether  they  arise 
immediately  from  the  object,  or  are  produced  by  the  creative 
power  of  the  mind,  or  are  deriv'd  from  the  author  of  our  being." 88 
Taking  into  account  the  supposition  of  critical  realism  that  the  dis- 
covery of  the  essences  relates  us  to  extra-mental  realities,  any 
one  instructed  by  Hume  might  say:  As  to  those  essences  which 
come  before  the  mind,  their  ultimate  conformity  to  reality  is  per- 

»*Pp.  166-167  (Mr.  Santayana). 

«•  P.  183  (Mr.  Santayana). 

>«  P.  184  (Mr.  Santayana). 

•*  Mr.  Santayana  'a  essay  amounts  to  showing  that  though  the  external 
world  can  not  be  proved  it  may  be  assumed  with  success.  But  it  is  not  an  exter- 
nal world  apart  from  experience  that  he  is  usually  talking  about.  He  seems  to 
bo  showing  rather  that  we  can  take  the  world  immediately  present  to  sense  as 
the  real  world.  This  is  quite  a  different  position  than  that  of  the  other  realists 
of  this  group.  Even  that,  however,  is  not  satisfactory.  It  seems  rather  to  be 
true  that  the  world  is  given  as  real  and  that  all  distinctions  we  discover,  as 
that  between  mind  and  object,  are  made  within  this  real  world.  Mr.  Santayana 
regrettably  baa  not  escaped  the  subjective  elements  of  the  British  tradition 
which  mar  his  otherwise  brilliant  volume  on  Reason  in  Common  Sense. 

88  Treatise  of  Human  Nature,  edition  of  Green  and  Grose,  Vol.  I,  p.  385. 


RELATIVITY,  OLD  AND  NEW  661 

fectly  unknowable  by  a  mind  which  has  no  direct  contact  with 
reality;  and  it  will  always  be  impossible  to  decide  with  certainty 
whether  they  correspond  to  external  objects  or  are  convenient  fic- 
tions for  the  practical,  but  not  the  theoretical,  concerns  of  life. 

A  candid  examination  by  the  critical  realists  of  the  divergences 
in  the  views  expressed  in  the  cooperative  volume  might  well  correct 
the  inadequacies  of  the  theory.  Those  who  are  nearest  to  Locke  are 
the  most  consistent  in  the  development  of  their  premises ;  and  those 
who  are  most  determined  to  be  realists  have  the  greatest  trouble 
with  the  Lockian  axiom  of  having  only  mental  contents  as  immedi- 
ate objects  of  the  mind.  In  other  words,  if  the  group  of  writers 
here  under  review  remain  "critical"  in  their  sense  of  the  word  as 
denying  the  direct  contact  of  the  mind  with  extra-mental  objects, 
they  have  no  logical  basis  for  their  realism;  and  if  they  wish  to  be 
realists  with  assurance,  they  have  to  cease  to  be  consistently  "criti- 
cal." As  it  is,  their  realism  should  be  called  hypothetical  or  pref- 
erential or  transcendental.  But  if  they  discard  the  assumption 
that  the  mind  does  not  come  into  direct  contact  with  external  ob- 
jects, realism  would  not  have  to  be  proved,  and  criticism  might  be- 
come more  relevant  to  human  concerns. 

STERLING  P.  LAMPBECHT. 
UNIVERSITY  or  ILLINOIS. 


"RELATIVITY,  OLD  AND  NEW" 

T  SHOULD  like  to  comment  briefly  on  Professor  Wadman's  article 
so  far  as  it  is  concerned  with  "objections"  to  my  own  re- 
marks.1 It  seems  to  me  that  he  has  failed  to  appreciate  my  aim, 
and  his  criticisms  are  therefore  almost  wholly  irrelevant.  Had  I 
been  dealing  with  the  aspects  of  relativity,  they  might  be  justified. 
But  I  confined  myself  to  some  aspects,  while  Professor  Wadman 
treats  of  points  which  I  deliberately  omitted.  My  purpose  was  to 
insist  that  the  theory  has  no  direct  bearing  on  the  relativity  of 
knowledge,  or  the  subjectivity  of  time  and  space  (p.  210).  Every- 
one is  familiar  with  the  extreme  views  which  have  been  advanced 
on  these  subjects;  and  from  that  standpoint  it  still  remains  true 
that  "the  philosophic  problems  of  objective  reality" — as  such  and 
in  general — remain  unaffected  by  recent  developments;  so  far  as 
they  are  concerned,  the  theory  is  a  "benevolent  neutral."  That 
"objective  reality  is  profoundly  changed  by  the  theory"  ("W.,  p. 
206)  is  obviously  true;  and  so  far  as  our  conceptual  handling  of 
i  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XVIII,  No.  8 ;  XIX,  No.  8.  To  avoid  confusion  in 
reference,  I  distinguish  Professor  Wadman's  pages  by  W. 


662  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  external  world  is  concerned,  and  subject  (further)  to  certain 
qualifications  which  I  still  consider  necessary  in  the  interests  of 
realism,  Professor  Wadman 's  presentation  contains  little  more 
than  what  I  have  myself  said  (pp.  214,  215).  But  prior  to  all  this 
there  is  the  still  more  fundamental  problem  of  the  character  of  ob- 
jective reality  in  general — not  simply  of  its  temporo-spatial  basis 
or  aspect;  and  it  was  with  these  preliminaries  of  the  whole  situa- 
tion that  I  endeavored  to  deal,  while  Professor  Wadman  makes  but 
the  barest  reference  to  them. 

But  when  we  pass  beyond  this  general  problem  to  others  more 
specific,  we  must  consider  where  the  distinction  is  to  be  drawn  be- 
tween the  philosophic  enquiry  and  the  scientific.  It  is,  of  course, 
impossible  to  be  dogmatic  here;  but  if  we  admit,  for  argument's 
sake,  that  the  subjects  discussed  by  Professor  Wadman  on  pp.  206, 
207,  are  truly  philosophical,  is  this  true  also  of  the  nature  of  the 
ether  or  the  atomic  nucleus,  of  Weyl's  extension  of  the  theory  or 
Painleve  's  and  Wiechert  's  criticisms  of  it,  or  of  the  quantum  theory 
or  the  physical  mechanism  of  heredity?  At  some  stage  all  these 
questions  fall  within  pure  science.  Exactly  where  must  remain 
always  a  matter  of  opinion;  but  a  great  part  of  Professor  Wad- 
man's  article  deals  with  what  I  should  myself  regard  as  scientific 
material;  and  we  must  here  recall  Einstein's  own  assertion  that 
"there  was  nothing  specially,  certainly  nothing  intentionally,  phil- 
osophical about"  his  investigation.2  We  may  compare  with  this — 
"It  would  be  wrong  to  associate  any  metaphysical  speculations  with 
the  introduction  of  the  four-dimensional  point  of  view";  "the 
theory  is  physical  and  not  metaphysical;  upon  what  particular 
basis  bare  matter  depends  is  a  question  not  for  the  philosopher 
but  the  physicist  to  decide. ' ' 8  We  must  recognize,  then,  that  what 
is  interesting  to  philosophers  is  not  always  of  philosophic  interest. 

The  role  of  "light  and  vision  in  normal  experience"  appears  to 
me  fundamentally  important.  The  theoretical  results  (W.,  p.  207) 
are  unquestionable,  though  to  speak  of  a  "fundamental  velocity 
that  is  invariant, ' '  but  which  is  still  not  the  velocity  of  some  actual 
entity,  seems  meaningless  abstraction.  But  the  question  still  re- 
mains— How  are  these  results  arrived  at  in  the  first  instance? 
Upon  what  is  "the  discovery  that  there  is  a  fundamental  invariant 
velocity"  based?  They  must  be  based  upon  observed  coincidences 
as  the  content  of  percephial  experience;  abolish  these,  and  nothing 
remains  whereon  to  found  a  theory  of  any  kind.  "We  observe  a 

*  Nature,  16  June,  1921,  p.  504.    Cf.  his  account  of  the  growth  of  his  theory 
in  Nature,  17  Feb.,  1921,  p.  782.    I  may  refer  to  the  fuller  discussion  of  these 
points  in  the  current  Volume  of  Mind. 

•  Schlick,  Space  and  Time,  p.  51.    Alexander,  Spinoza  and  Time,  pp.  39,  45. 


RELATIVITY,  OLD  AND  NEW  663 

coincidence,  an  event.  In  each  several  map  of  the  universe  the 
event  is  uniquely  recorded  as  a  single  coincidence.  The  only  pre- 
cise observations  are  those  of  coincidences. ' ' 4  But  why,  again, 
should  "c"  remain  paradoxically  invariant  for  all  observers?5 
Once  more  because  the  perceived  light  phenomena  furnish  the  sole 
available  means  for  their  own  investigation,  while  light  travels  with 
finite  velocity.  The  physicist  is  here  left  with  nothing  to  hoist  him- 
self by  except  his  own  waist  belt ;  the  inevitable  result  is  invariance, 
and  the  paradox  in  both  cases  is  merely  apparent.  So  far  as  the 
indispensable  initial  observations  are  concerned,  therefore,  it  is  the 
non-existence  of  any  phenomenon  which  can  be  perceived  and  com- 
pared with  light  signals  that  is  fundamental.  "We  have  not  taken 
account,"  asserts  Einstein  in  recounting  the  development  of  his 
theory,  "of  the  inaccuracy  involved  by  the  finiteness  of  the  velocity 
of  light";6  "if  some  new  kind  of  ray  with  a  higher  speed  were 
discovered,  it  would  perhaps  tend  to  displace  light  signals  and  light 
velocity. ' ' 7  Finally,  if  we  assume  gravitational  impulses  arising 
which  had  an  infinite  velocity,  and  also  that  we  could  directly  per- 
ceive their  effects,8  relativity  phenomena  might  be  excluded  from 
consideration  altogether. 

In  conclusion,  what  Professor  Wadman  calls  my  "exposition  of 
the  transformation  in  terms  of  sound"  (p.  206)  was  offered  as  noth- 
ing more  than  a  somewhat  crude  illustration  based  on  "familiar 
occurrences."  When  the  article  was  written  many  readers  found 
an  insuperable  difficulty  in  discovering  analogies  to  the  new  theory 
in  ordinary  experience.  It  still  remains  true,  I  think,  that  to  them 
Professor  Wadman 's  concise  outline  would  have  been  incompre- 
hensible. I  certainly  did  not  regard  it  as  a  wholly  satisfactory 
substitute,  and  the  "Prince  of  Denmark"  note  merely  emphasized 
the  insufficiency  of  the  analogy;  it  is  unfortunate  that  no  precise 
parallel  can  be  offered;  but  the  actual  phenomena  are,  of  course, 
unique ;  "  c  plays  a  unique  part  in  Nature. ' ' 9  Professor  Wadman 
suggests  that  my  imaginary  observers  should  be  "lacking  in  other 
respects  than  eyesight"  (W.,  p.  206)  ;  but  as  they  already  derived 

•*  Cunningham,  Relativity  and  the  Electron  Theory,  pp.  93,  126.  Cf.  Brose, 
The  Theory  of  Belativity,  p.  14 ;  Eddington,  Space,  Time  and  Gravitation,  p.  87. 
Both  "coincidence"  and  "observation"  are  fundamental. 

o  I  omit  gravitation  for  brevity. 

«  The  Theory  of  Eelativity,  p.  10.  Of.  Campbell,  Physics,  The  Elements, 
p.  552. 

*  Eddington,  Space,  Time  and  Gravitation,  p.  60. 

s  An  assumption  on  all  fours  with  Professor  Wadman 's  hyperesthesia, 
p.  206.  The  infinity  of  gravitational  transmission  is,  I  think,  still  an  open 
question. 

•  Schlick,  op.  cit.,  p.  15. 


<;r,t  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

"all  their  knowledge  solely  from  hearing"  (p.  212)  it  seems  to  me 
that  any  further  loss  would  reduce  them  to  helpless  dependence  on 
their  "unconscious";  or,  at  the  most,  transform  them  into  behavior- 
ists. 

J.  E.  TURNER. 
LIVERPOOL,  ENGLAND. 

BOOK  REVIEWS 

Psychologie  der  Kunst.  Bd.  I.  RICH.  MULLER-FREIENFELS.  Leip- 
zig :  B.  G.  Teubner.  1922.  Pp.  viii  +  248. 
The  first  edition  of  this  book  appeared  in  two  volumes  in  1912. 
The  present  revision  has  been  so  thorough  and  the  changes  in  both 
form  and  content  are  so  numerous  that  it  seems  almost  like  a  new 
book.  The  arrangement  of  the  topics  is  somewhat  different,  much 
new  material  has  been  added,  some  of  the  latest  theories  and  tend- 
encies such  as  the  Freudian  have  been  considered,  more  examples 
have  been  used  and  a  few  illustrations  of  paintings,  designs  and 
music  are  now  included.  Above  all  the  esthetic  principle  of  unity 
is  more  closely  followed  in  the  composition  so  that  the  text  holds 
together,  a  factor  which  considerably  increases  the  pleasure  of  the 
reader. 

It  would  be  tedious  and  unprofitable  to  give  a  detailed  enumera- 
tion of  the  changes  that  have  been  made.  I  will,  therefore,  de- 
scribe briefly  the  more  important  ideas  even  though  some  of  them 
have  already  appeared  in  the  first  edition. 

The  author  takes  exception  to  a  theoretical,  philosophical  dis- 
cussion of  esthetics  in  the  belief  that  the  only  method  to  be  pursued 
is  an  empirical,  psychological  one.  Although  I  agree  with  him 
in  general  in  his  remarks  about  methods,  I  do  not  think  he  is  justi- 
fied in  his  statement  that  possibly  the  questionnaire  method  is  more 
important  than  the  experimental  procedure.  In  psychology  the  re- 
sults of  questionnaires  are  of  doubtful  value.  The  situation  is 
worse  in  esthetics  especially  when  the  questions  are  sent  to  artists. 
Experience  soon  teaches  one  that  what  they  say  about  their  meth- 
ods and  feelings  has  frequently  little  relation  to  the  actual  facts. 
Even  the  descriptions  by  authors  of  their  methods  of  work,  such  as 
Poe's  account  of  the  composition  of  the  Raven,  can  not  be  accepted 
uncritically. 

The  author  accepts  the  traditional,  philosophical  definition  of 
an  esthetic  object,  namely,  one  whose  value  is  self-contained  (ihren 
Wert  in  sich  selber  tragt).  Later,  however,  he  broadens  his  con- 
cept by  adding  the  physiological  interpretation  that  in  the  percep- 
tion of  beauty  there  is  an  adequate  reaction  of  the  organism,  which 
is  productive  of  pleasure. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  665 

Art  is  carefully  defined  and  shown  to  be  a  special  type  of 
beauty  differentiated  from  the  rest  of  the  field  of  esthetics  by  the 
presence  of  form.  Simple  colors  are  not  yet  art  because  they  lack 
form  and  the  perceptions  through  the  lower  senses  are  not  art  be- 
cause they  lack  permanent  form.  Undoubtedly  these  are  practical 
distinctions,  but  theoretically  one  must  take  exception  to  the  state- 
ment that  single  colors  lack  form,  for  there  is  a  relation  of  hue, 
saturation  and  brightness  in  every  color,  which  gives  it  a  form 
quality.  The  author  also  maintains  that  there  are  certain  forms 
of  art,  such  as  statues  of  emperors,  religious  pictures,  etc.,  which 
are  not  esthetic  objects.  After  all  is  this  not  a  superficial  distinc- 
tion? Whether  these  are  esthetic  objects  or  not  depends  upon  the 
state  of  mind  of  the  observer.  Notwithstanding  their  original 
purpose,  such  objects  may  very  well  be  enjoyed  later  for  their  in- 
trinsic beauty,  if  they  happen  to  possess  that  quality. 

Considerable  space  is  given  to  empathy  and  motor  responses 
and  the  importance  of  such  responses  is  strongly  emphasized,  al- 
though the  author  is  conservative  to  the  extent  that  he  does  not  be- 
lieve that  empathy  is  essential  to  art  appreciation.  The  balance  is, 
however,  tilted  in  the  direction  of  empathic  experience,  which  fact 
is  interesting  in  connection  with  the  recent  attitude  of  Mr.  Bui- 
lough  in  brushing  aside  the  entire  question  of  empathy  with  the 
remark  that  the  theory  of  empathy  was  disproved  some  years  ago 
by  psychologists. 

Dr.  Miiller-Freienfels  describes  the  various  imaginal  types,  such 
as  visual,  motor,  etc.,  and  gives  examples  of  some  of  them.  The 
visual  type,  for  example,  is  illustrated  by  a  picture  by  Monet  and 
the  motor  type  by  one  by  van  Gogh.  Throughout  the  book,  how- 
ever, the  author  refrains  from  stating  what  types  and  attitudes  are 
intrinsically  esthetic.  Judgments  of  values  have  been  left  for  a 
second  volume.  In  this  book  there  is  merely  described  the  state  of 
mind  of  the  man  who  thinks  he  is  an  artist  or  passes  for  one,  and 
the  individual  who  at  least  uses  esthetic  terms,  even  though  his 
judgment  may  not  be  based  on  a  truly  esthetic  experience.  For 
instance,  the  author  quite  rightly  believes  that  both  the  emotions 
and  the  intellect  are  involved  in  an  esthetic  reaction,  with  the 
emphasis  as  a  rule  on  the  emotions.  He  divides  individuals,  how- 
ever, into  two  types,  the  empathic  and  the  contemplative,  and  some 
of  the  descriptions  of  this  latter  distinctly  intellectual  and  reflec- 
tive type  seem  to  me  to  refer  to  the  critic  rather  than  to  the  one 
who  is  enjoying  beauty.  It  is  stretching  the  term  to  call  the  cold- 
blooded reasoning  of  the  critic  or  even  his  reflections  upon  his  own 
mental  and  emotional  processes  an  esthetic  experience,  although 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

such  an  attitude  often  passes  for  the  enjoyment  of  beauty  and, 
therefore,  with  the  utmost  catholicity  is  included  by  the  author  in 
his  classifications  and  descriptions. 

There  is  an  extensive  discussion  of  feelings  and  emotions,  which 
is  rather  antiquated  and  probably  the  least  valuable  part  of  the 
book.  The  author  has  tried  at  all  times  to  be  empirical  and  that 
he  often  falls  back  upon  an  analysis  of  his  own  mind  rather  than 
refer  to  experimental  results  is  due  not  alone  to  his  lack  of 
knowledge  of  some  of  the  more  recent  experimental  researches,  but 
also  to  the  fact  that  in  experimental  esthetics  psychology  has  still 
a  large,  unploughed  field  ahead.  To  mention  two  of  the  many  prob- 
lems, there  is  that  of  the  consciousness  of  self  in  esthetic  experi- 
ence and  the  feeling  of  unreality.  Both  questions  should  be  sub- 
mitted to  further  experimentation.  Mere  discussion  will  not  decide 
whether  Lange  is  correct  in  his  contention  that  the  feeling  of  un- 
reality is  essential  to  art  appreciation  or  the  author  in  his  belief 
that  art  is  not  unreal  but  a-real. 

The  book  is  useful  both  for  the  study  and  for  the  teaching  of 
esthetics  and  even  those  who  are  already  familiar  with  the  first  edi- 
tion will  find  this  revision  profitable  reading. 

H.  S.  LANGPELD. 
HABVARD  UNivmsirr. 

An  Introduction  to  Psychology.     SUSAN   S.   BRIERLEY.     London. 

Methuen  and  Co.    1921.    Pp.  151. 

To  make  this  review  the  most  useful,  it  is  well  to  quote  from  the 
outside  title  page  as  follows :  ' '  This  book  is  written  to  meet  the  first 
needs  of  the  non-professional  students.  The  beginner  is  introduced 
to  certain  main  lines  of  thought,  based  upon  a  biological  approach  to 
psychology  and  from  this  point  of  view  the  theory  of  psycho-analysis 
is  brought  into  relation  with  normal  psychology  and  with  experi- 
mental behaviorism."  The  volume  fulfills  this  purpose  and  is  an 
admirable  example  of  multum  in  parvo. 

The  author  follows  McDougall  in  the  main,  but  shows  an  inde- 
pendence and  clearness  of  thought  which  can  express  itself  with 
simplicity.  The  pages  abound  in  happy  definitions  causing  muddled 
trains  of  thought  to  fall  into  logical  orderliness  with  a  kaleidescopic 
mano3uvre.  "The  'nature'  of  each  creature  is  just  the  sum  of  those 
manifold  tendencies  to  behaviour  which  it  exhibits  on  each  proper  oc- 
casion." "When,  however,  displacement  occurs  in  a  form  socially 
useful  and  acceptable  it  is  now  common  to  speak  of  it  as  sublimation 
from  the  Latin  sublimare, — to  lift  up."  "The  'neurotic'  appears 
to  be  one  who  is  more  or  less  permanently  unable  to  bear  the  full 


BOOK  REVIEWS  667 

pressure  of  real  life  and  tries  to  retire  from  it  into  the  world  of 
phantasy  where  immediate  satisfaction  of  desire  without  effort  can  be 
achieved. ' '  The  word  hormone  is  substituted  for  libido  as  being  less 
ambiguous.  Man  is  a  "learning  animal"  rather  than  a  rational  one. 

The  outstanding  feature  of  the  work  is  the  exposition  of  the 
unconscious  as  joining  with  the  conscious  in  a  normal  procedure  and 
psycho-analysis  is  shown  to  be  simply  a  technical  elaboration  of 
ordinary  introspective  self-analysis.  It  is  a  book  for  the  market 
place  and  the  easy  chair  rather  than  for  academic  halls ;  for  the  man 
who  wishes  to  ' '  know  himself ' '  rather  than  to  know  what  others  think 
of  him. 

LUCINDA  PEARL  BOQGS. 

UEBANA,  ILLINOIS. 

The  Dalton  Laboratory  Plan.    EVELYN  DEWBY.    New  York:  E.  P. 

Button  &  Co.    173  pp. 

The  dissatisfaction  with  existing  educational  practices  which 
has  developed  increasingly  during  the  past  decade  in  this  country 
and  in  England  particularly  during  and  since  the  War  has  led  to 
a  critical  valuation  of  both  the  curriculum  and  methods.  The  Dal- 
ton Laboratory  Plan  is  an  attempt  to  overcome  many  of  the  diffi- 
culties that  result  from  class  instruction  and  the  tendency  to  a 
lockstep  method  which  caters  to  the  pupil  of  average  ability  and 
neglects  the  dull  and  the  gifted.  Class  instruction,  it  is  charged, 
implies  the  progress  of  all  pupils  at  the  same  rate  and  throws  the 
responsibility  on  the  teacher  rather  than  on  willing  cooperation 
and  independent  study  by  the  pupil.  The  Plan  aims  to  train  the 
pupil  to  assume  responsibility  for  his  own  progress,  to  realize  the 
pleasure  of  self-education,  to  organize  his  work  and  distribute  his 
time  among  his  required  studies  to  suit  his  own  needs  and  abilities, 
and  to  secure  help  from  teachers,  fellow-pupils,  books  and  other 
resources  as  occasion  demands.  The  function  of  the  teacher  is  to 
make  periodical  assignments,  monthly  according  to  the  Plan,  which 
the  pupil  is  under  contract  to  perform.  In  place  of  class-room  in- 
struction, assignments  of  work  from  day  to  day,  and  the  use  of  a 
limited  number  of  textbooks,  separate  rooms  are  equipped  with 
reference  and  other  material  for  each  subject  or  groups  of  sub- 
jects; these  are  the  laboratories  to  which  the  pupils  resort,  irre- 
spective of  their  class  membership,  to  fulfil  their  contracts.  An 
elaborate  system  of  daily  records,  indicating  progress,  has  been 
devised  for  pupils  and  teachers. 

The  advantages  claimed  for  the  Plan  are  that  each  pupil  may 
advance  at  his  own  rate,  that  methods  of  study  and  work  are  re- 


668  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

quired  which  prevail  outside  the  school  so  that  there  is  no  break  in 
gauge  between  life  in  school  and  life  outside  the  school,  and  that 
the  qualities  essential  in  a  democracy — self-reliance,  initiative,  in- 
dependence of  judgment — are  cultivated.  For  the  present,  the 
Plan  is  not  concerned  with  changes  in  the  curriculum. 

The  method  derives  its  name  from  the  adoption  of  the  Plan  in 
the  high  school  at  Dalton,  Mass.  There  is  no  evidence,  however, 
from  Miss  Dewey's  book  that  the  Plan,  inaugurated  at  Dalton  in 
1919,  has  been  carried  out  in  its  entirety  in  accordance  with  the 
principles  enunciated  by  Miss  Helen  Parkhurst  and  practiced  by 
her  in  the  Children's  University  School  of  New  York.  The  Plan 
has  received  a  greater  welcome  in  England  than  in  this  country 
and  has  there  attained  the  dignity  of  a  cult  in  the  establishment 
of  the  Dalton  Association.  Few  educators  in  the  United  States 
were  familiar  with  the  Plan  under  its  present  name  until  it  was 
re-imported  from  England,  although  in  many  of  its  essentials  it 
has  for  some  years  been  practiced  at  the  San  Francisco  Normal 
School  and  in  the  public  schools  of  Winnetka,  Illinois. 

While  Miss  Dewey  has  performed  a  useful  service  in  thus  bring- 
ing the  Dalton  Plan  to  the  attention  of  American  educators,  she  is, 
in  spite  of  her  introductory  warning  that  "it  is  not  possible  to 
present  it  (the  Plan)  as  a  tested  and  proved  system,"  too  apt  to 
become  more  enthusiastic  than  the  experiment  warrants.  Ignoring 
the  recent  contributions  of  educational  psychology,  she  generalizes 
too  freely  about  the  possibilities  of  cultivating  a  sense  of  responsi- 
bility, initiative,  self-reliance,  and  resourcefulness  in  all  pupils,  a 
generalization  that  is  not  justified  by  the  testimony  of  teachers  and 
pupils  quoted  in  the  book.  However  alluring  Miss  Dewey's  theory 
may  be  that  "education  today  must  consist  in  learning  to  learn, 
finding  out  about  knowledge  and  what  it  is  for,  so  it  can  be  acquired 
and  used  when  it  is  needed,"  the  impossibility  of  achieving  this 
task  is  indicated  by  the  theory  of  individual  differences  and  ex- 
perience with  college  and  university  students.  The  enthusiastic 
reformer  is  too  prone  to  overlook  the  progress,  slow  but  real,  made 
by  the  public  schools,  just  as  Miss  Dewey  overlooks  the  extensive 
literature  of  the  last  ten  years  on  "How  to  think"  and  "How  to 
study."  Into  some  of  the  administrative  difficulties  of  the  Plan 
it  is  unnecessary  to  enter  here,  although  the  question  might  be  raised 
whether  a  monthly  contract  is  not  as  likely  to  militate  against  free 
development  just  as  much  as  does  the  daily  assignment.  On  the  whole 
the  value  of  Miss  Dewey's  book  and  Miss  Parkhurst 's  experiment  lies 
in  directing  attention  to  existing  weaknesses  in  the  schools,  but  salva- 
tion does  not  lie  in  any  one  method  or  in  any  particular  experiment, 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

especially  when  it  is  not  subjected  to  such  objective  and  scientific  tests 
as  have  already  been  devised.  There  is  a  danger,  too,  that  in  our 
preoccupation  with  the  pupils'  needs  which  results  from  time  to 
time  in  new  plans,  new  methods,  new  devices,  the  supreme  need  of 
education,  good  teachers  possessing  the  self-reliance,  initiative,  re- 
sourcefulness and  independence,  so  much  desired  for  pupils,  will 
be  forgotten.  About  these  Miss  Dewey  has  too  little  to  say,  forget- 
ting that  any  plan  or  method,  strictly  pursued,  may  without  good 
teachers  in  time  become  formal. 

I.  L.  KANDEL. 
TEACHERS  COLLEGE, 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


JOUENALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

REVUE  DE  THEOLOGIE  ET  DE  PHILOSOPHIE.  Vol.  X,  No.  44.  De  la 
religion  comme  principe  indispensable  a  la  vie  de  1'humanite:  P. 
Bridel.  Franz  Leenhardt  (1846-1922)  :  P.  Daulte.  Partis  et  con- 
flits  d'idees  dans  1  'anglicanisme  contemporain :  R.  Werner.  Le  prag- 
matisme  religieux:  A.  Reymond.  L'energie  universelle:  J.  de  la 
Harpe. 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  BULLETIN.  Vol.  19,  No.  8.  Contributions  to  the 
History  of  Psychology— 1916-^1921 :  C.  R.  Griffith.  The  Evolution  of 
Psychological  Textbooks  Since  1912:  J.  R.  Kantor.  A  Note  on 
Theories  of  Learning :  J.  Peterson. 

ZEITSCHRIFT  FUR  PSYCHOLOGEE.  Bd.  90,  Heft  3-6.  Untersuchun- 
gen  liber  die  sog.  Zollnerschen  anorthoskopischen  Zerrbilder:  H. 
Rotschild.  Neue  Untersuchungen  zum  Problem  des  Verhaltnisses 
von  Akkommodation  und  Konvergenz  zur  Wahrnehmung  der  Tiefe : 
J.  Bappert.  Ueber  die  Erblichkeit  der  musikalischen  Begabung: 
V.  Haecker  und  Th.  Ziehen.  Ueber  den  Einfluss  der  Grossenvariier- 
ung  bei  Gedachtnisleistungen :  M.  Floors.  Neue  Untersuchungen  zu 
C'inem  Fall  von  abnormen  Datengedachtnis :  R.  Hennig. 

BRITISH  JOURNAL  OP  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  XIII,  Part  2.  October, 
1922.  The  Relations  of  Complex  and  Sentiment,  (I)  :  W.  H.  R. 
Rivers;  (II)  A.  G.  Tansley;  (III)  A.  F.  Shand;  (IV)  T.  H.  Pear; 
(V)  B.  Hart;  (VI)  C.  S.  Myers.  A  Note  on  some  Dreams  of  a  Nor- 
mal Person:  M.  Sturt.  Motor  Capacity  with  Special  Reference  to 
Vocational  Guidance:  B.  Muscio.  A  Vindication  of  the  Resonance 
Hypothesis  of  Audition.  V:  H.  Hartridge.  Suspicion:  A.  Shand. 
A  Note  on  Local  Fatigue  in  the  Auditory  System:  F.  Bartlett  and 
H.  Mark. 

REVUE  DE  METAPHYSIQUE  ET  DE  MORALE.  29"  Annee,  No.  3.  La 
philosophic  d'fimile  Boutroux:  L.  Brunschvicg.  L'oeuvre  de  Pierre 
Boutroux :  L.  Brunschvicg.  Les  principes  du  calcul  des  probabilites : 


670  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

J.  Hadamard.  Analyse  de  1'acte  libre  public  par  L.  Dugas:  J.  Le- 
quyer.  Essai  sur  la  system  at  isati  on  du  savoir  scientifique:  R. 
Hubert. 

THE  AMERICAN  JOURNAL  OF  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  XXXIII,  No.  4. 
Film,  Surface,  and  Bulky  Colors  and  Their  Intermediates:  M.  F. 
Martin.  Can  the  Psychophysical  Experiment  Reconcile  Introspec- 
tionists  and  Objectivists? :  J.  R.  Kantor.  Movements  of  Pursuit  and 
Avoidance  as  Expressions  of  Simple  Feeling:  P.  T.  Young.  Diotic 
Tonal  Volumes  as  a  Function  of  Difference  of  Phase :  H.  M.  Halver- 
son.  An  Experimental  Study  of  Henning's  System  of  Olfactory 
Qualities :  M .  K.  MacDonald.  A  Study  of  Liminal  Sound  Intensities 
and  the  Application  of  Weber's  Law  to  Tones  of  Different  Pitch: 
M.  Guernsey.  The  Effect  of  Change  of  Intensity  upon  the  Upper 
Limit  of  Hearing :  E.  F.  Holler.  A  Study  of  the  Relation  of  Dis- 
tracted Motor  Performance  to  Performance  in  an  Intelligence  Test: 
M .  A.  Tinker.  The  Areal  and  Punctiform  Integration  of  Warmth  and 
Pressure :  I.  Bershansky.  The  Integration  of  Warmth  and  Pressure : 
L.  Knight. 

THE  MONIST.  Vol.  XXXII,  No.  4.  Ethics,  Morality,  and  Meta- 
physical Assumptions:  L.  A.  Reid.  Perception  and  Nature:  H.  E. 
Cunningham.  A  Criticism  of  Critical  Realism :  C.  E.  M.  Joad.  The 
Spirit  of  Research :  J.  B.  Shaw.  A  Comparison  of  the  Ethical  Philos- 
ophies of  Spinoza  and  Hobbes:  V.  T.  Thayer.  The  Logic  of  Dis- 
covery: R.  D.  Carmichael. 

Bergson,  Henri :  Mind-Energy.  Lectures  and  Essays,  translated 
by  H.  Wildon  Carr.  London :  Macmillan  Co.  1922.  212  pp. 

Conger,  George  Perrigo :  Theories  of  Macrocosms  and  Microcosms 
in  the  History  of  Philosophy.  Columbia  University  Press.  1922. 
xviii  -|-  149  pp. 

Gunn,  J.  Alexander :  Modern  French  Philosophy :  A  Study  of  the 
Development  since  Comte.  London :  T.  Fisher  Unwin.  1922. 

Laing,  B.  M. :  A  Study  of  Moral  Problems.  New  York :  Macmil- 
lan Co.  1922.  279  pp. 

Lalo,  Charles :  La  Beaute  et  1  'intinct  sexuel.  Paris :  Ernest  Flam- 
marion.  1922.  188  pp. 

Pratt,  James  Bissett :  Matter  and  Spirit.  New  York :  Macmillan 
Co.  1922.  230  pp. 

Osterhout,  W.  J.  V. :  Injury,  Recovery  and  Death  in  Relation  to 
Conductivity  and  Permeability.  Philadelphia :  J.  B.  Lippincott  Co. 
1922.  259pp. 

Vivante,  Leone :  Delia  Intelligenza  nell '  Espressione.  Rome :  P. 
Maglione  &  C.  Strini.  1922.  227  pp. 

Hoffding,  Meijer,  Brunschvicg  and  others:  Chronicon  Spinozan- 
um.  Tomus  Primus.  The  Hague:  Societatis  Spinozanae.  1921. 
326  pp. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  671 

Moore,  Thomas  Verner :  Percy  Bysshe  Shelley ;  An  Introduction 
to  the  Study  of  Character.  Psychological  Monographs,  Volume 
XXXI,  No.  2 :  Psychological  Studies  from  The  Catholic  University 
of.  America.  Princeton:  Psychological  Review  Company.  1922. 
62  pp. 

Phalen,  Adolf:  Ueber  die  Relativitat  der  Raumund  Zeitbestim- 
mungen.  Skrifter  utgifna  af  K.  Humanistiska  Vetenskaps-Sam- 
f undet  i  Uppsala :  XXI :  4.  Leipzig :  Otto  Harrassowitz.  1922. 
176  pp. 

Tarner,  George  Edward:  Some  Remarks  on  the  Axioms  and 
Postulates  of  Athetic  Philosophy.  Cambridge,  England :  Deighton, 
BeU  and  Company,  Ltd.  1922.  44  pp.  2/6. 

Die  Philosophie  der  Gegenwart  in  Selbstdarstellungen.  Raymund 
Schmidt,  editor.  Volume  III.  Leipzig:  Felix  Meiner.  1922. 
234  pp. 

NOTES  AND  NEWS 

The  founders  of  Societas  Spinozana  solicit  the  interest  of  the 
public  in  their  enterprise  of  promoting  the  study  of  Spinoza  and  of 
his  philosophy.  The  society  aims  to  be  international  in  character. 
Its  headquarters  are  at  The  Hague  and  its  Curators  are  Professor 
Harald  Hoffding  (Copenhagen),  Dr.  William  Meijer  (The  Hague), 
Sir  Frederick  Pollock  (London),  Professor  Leon  Brunschvicg 
(Paris),  and  Dr.  Carl  Gebhardt  (Frankfort  on  the  Main). 

A  volume  of  studies  (Chronicon  Spinozanum)  is  to  be  published 
annually,  the  first  of  which  has  already  appeared,  containing  articles 
in  Dutch,  French,  English,  German,  and  Italian  by  a  group  of  writers 
including  Hoffding,  Pollack,  Brunschvicg,  and  Delbos.  The  annual 
is  to  be  issued  only  to  members  of  the  Association.  The  secretary  of 
the  United  States  is  A.  S.  Oko,  Hebrew  Union  College  Library,  Cin- 
cinnati, Ohio. 

A  Nietzsche-Gesellschaft  now  follows  a  Kant-Gesellschafte  and  a 
Schopenhauer-Gesellschafte  in  Germany,  with  the  emphasis,  however, 
on  the  practical  phases  of  Nietzsche 's  thought  and  his  inspiration  for 
the  personal  life.  Stress  is  particularly  laid  on  his  ' '  good-European ' ' 
standpoint,  and  his  separation  from  the  ordinary  political,  i.e.,  nation- 
alistic, movements  of  recent  times.  Among  the  Vorstand  are  Thomas 
Mann  and  Hugo  von  Hofmannsthal.  Headquarters  are  in  Munich 
(Schackstrasse,  4)  and  an  international  membership  is  desired. 

Professor  A.  N.  Whitehead,  President  of  the  Aristotelian  Society, 
delivered  the  inaugural  address  on  November  6th,  1922,  on  the 
subject  of  "Uniformity  and  Contingency."  Our  awareness  of  na- 


672  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

ture,  he  declared,  consists  of  the  projection  of  sense-objects  into  a 
spatio-temporal  continuum  either  within  or  without  our  bodies.  But 
"projection"  implies  a  sensorium  which  is  the  origin  of  projection. 
This  sensorium  is  within  our  bodies,  and  each  sense-object  can  only 
be  described  as  located  in  any  region  of  space-time  by  reference  to 
a  particular  simultaneous  location  of  a  bodily  sensorium.  The  proc- 
ess  of  projection  consists  in  our  awareness  of  an  irreducible  many- 
termed  relation  between  the  sense-object  in  question,  the  bodily 
sensorium,  and  the  space-time  continuum,  and  it  also  requires  our 
awareness  of  that  continuum  as  stratified  into  layers  of  simultaneity, 
whose  temporal  thickness  depends  on  the  specious  present.  If  this 
account  of  nature  be  accepted,  then  space-time  must  be  uniform. 
For  any  part  of  it  settles  the  scheme  of  relations  for  the  whole  ir- 
respective of  the  particular  mode  in  which  any  other  part  of  it, 
in  the  future  or  the  past  or  elsewhere  in  space,  may  exhibit  the  in- 
gression  of  sense-objects.  Accordingly,  the  scheme  of  relations  must 
be  exhibited  with  a  systematic  uniformity.  We  have  here  the  pri- 
mary ground  of  uniformity  in  nature. 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  25  DECEMBER  7,  1922 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  COSMOLOGY  OF  WILLIAM  JAMES 


WILLIAM  JAMES  clarified  and  illumined  psychology  and  phi- 
losophy more  inspiringly  than  any  other  man  of  recent  gen- 
erations; and  in  doing  this  he  furnished  momentous  guidance  for 
all  future  efforts  to  solve  the  fundamental  problems  of  mankind. 

A  proper  review  of  James's  work  as  a  whole  would  justify  this 
estimate  of  him;  and  would  most  richly  emphasize  the  tribute  that 
mankind  owes  to  his  genius.  Such  a  complete  review  should  be 
made.  But  it  would  be  too  long  for  my  present  space.  And  I  will 
examine,  here,  only  his  main  conceptions  of  the  universe. 

Two  of  these  main  conceptions  James  stated  definitely:  The 
entire  universe  is  constituted  solely  of  "one  general  sort  of  stuff." 
And  it  is  a  "Plural  Universe."  There  can  be  no  doubt  that  by 
"Plural  Universe,"  James  meant  a  universe  comprising  many  minds; 
and  as  distinguished  from  a  universe  declared  to  comprise  one  "Ab- 
solute Mind. ' '  But  this  does  not  preclude  the  possibility  that  James 
conceived  certain  stuff  and  things  to  exist,  not  in  any  mind.  And 
often  he  used  language  difficult  to  interpret  otherwise  than  in  accord 
with  such  a  conception.  True,  he  sometimes  declared  that  he  always 
dealt  with  "Berkeleyan  things"  only;  and  seemed  by  this  to  imply 
that  no  things  ever  exist  save  as  components  of  one  or  more  minds. 
Nevertheless,  one's  chief  difficulty  in  studying  James's  writings  is  that 
of  reconciling  his  many  declarations. 

As  to  what  James  meant  by  "  a  mind, ' '  he  often  used  the  phrase 
in  ways  implying  two  fundamentally  different  sorts  of  minds,  or  in 
ways  hard  to  interpret  in  any  one  meaning.  And  these  I  now  pro- 
ceed to  consider,  inasmuch  as  they  double  the  difficulty  of  discover- 
ing how  James  presumed  any  one  mind  to  be  distinguished  from 
more  than  one,  and  every  mind  to  be  distinguished  from  every  other 
mind — whatever  the  sort  or  sorts  of  minds  be  involved — and  because 
they  greatly  increase  the  difficulty  of  discovering  how  James  divided 
the  "one  sort  of  stuff"  in  the  universe — whether  wholly  between 
' '  plural ' '  minds  of  one  sort  or  another,  or  in  a  way  leaving  some  of 
the  stuff  in  no  mind. 

One  of  the  two  meanings  of  "the  mind"  possibly  implied  by 

673 


674  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPU  1 

James  is  one  that  he  seems  generally  to  have  used  when  identifying 
the  mind  with  \vlmt  he  also  called  "tin-  stream  of  thought";  and  when 
M>  living  this  meaning,  James  seems  intentionally  to  have  described 
the  mind  or  stream  so  involved,  as  being  constituted  of  stuff  pri- 
marily and  commonly  destitute  of  consciousness  and  requiring  some- 
thing other  than  itself  in  order  to  become  conscious  occasionally. 
Moreover,  James  seems  to  have  implied  the  quite  other  meaning  of 
"the  mind"  only  when  speaking  of  such  conscious  occasions;  and  he 
deliberately  declared  consciousness  to  be  a  something  that  "comes  in" 
at  a  distinct  stage  of  biologic  evolution,  thus  making  doubtful  how 
he  conceived  prior  minds  if  he  conceived  any.  Therefore,  by  way  of 
discovering  how  James  divided  his  "one  sort  of  stuff"  into  his  "Plu- 
ral Universe"  and  what  sort  of  mind  or  minds  he  did  or  did  not 
wittingly  conceive  for  that  purpose,  I  now  turn  to  his  teachings 
regarding  consciousness. 

In  James's  paper  "Does  Consciousness  Exist?"  he  declared  that 
consciousness  does  not  exist,  but  is  an  "  act  of  addition  or  appropria- 
tion"; and  defined  consciousness  to  be  "awareness  of  one's  being 
added  to  that  being." 

One  wonders  how  "awareness"  can  be  "added,"  yet  not  "exist"! 
And  as  he  used  a  certain  "pen-experience"  for  expounding  his 
theme,  I  quote  what  his  paper  says  about  this  experience:  "To  be 
'conscious'  means  not  simply  to  be,  but  to  be  reported,  known,  to 
have  awareness  of  one's  being  added  to  that  being;  and  this  is  just 
what  happens  when  the  appropriative  experience  supervenes.  The 
pen-experience  in  its  original  immediacy  is  not  aware  of  itself,  it 
simply  is,  and  the  second  experience  is  required  for  what  we  call 
Awareness  of  it  to  occur.  It  is  indeed  'mine'  only  as  it  is  felt  as 
mine,  and  is  'yours'  only  as  it  is  felt  as  yours.  But  it  is  felt  as 
neither  by  itself,  but  only  when  'owned'  by  our  several  remember- 
ing experiences,  just  as  one  undivided  estate  is  owned  by  several 
heirs.  .  .  .  Since  the  acquisition  of  conscious  quality  on  the  part  of 
an  experience  depends  upon  a  context  coming  to  it,  it  follows  that 
(the  pen-experience)  can  not  strictly  be  called  conscious  at  all." 

This  passage  says  nothing  about  any  sort  of  mind ;  but  it  excites 
many  questions.  It  declares  that  the  pen-experience  "in  its  origi- 
nal immediacy,"  "can  not  strictly  be  called  conscious  at  all." 
Is  it  at  that  moment  an  "immediate"  part  of  some  unconscious 
"mind"  or  "stream"?  Only  "later,"  does  it  become  "mine" 
and  "felt  as  mine."  What  Is  the  "me"  of  which  it  so  becomes 
consciously  "mine"?  Inasmuch  as,  apparently,  it  "feels,"  is  this 
"me"  of  itself  a  conscious  mind?  Apparently  it  is  the  "second 
experience"  or  "context"  required  for  awareness  of  the  pen-expe- 
rience "to  occur,"  and  required  to  "own"  and  to  "appropriate" 


THE  COSMOLOGY  OF  WILLIAM  JAMES  675 

the  pen-experience.  But  if  this  be  the  "me"  that  we  seek,  how 
does  this  "me"  or  "experience"  differ  from  the  pen-experience, 
both  as  regards  "experience,"  and  as  regards  "stuff"?  If  it  be  a 
context  of  awareness  only,  it  can  no  more  exist,  according  to 
James,  than  does  consciousness.  And  if  it  be  a  "stuff"  experience 
of  one  general  sort  with  the  pen-experience,  and  differ  essentially 
from  it  only  in  performing  an  "act  of  appropriation,"  just  what 
is  this  "second  experience"  that  James  so  strangely  fails  to  de- 
scribe more  definitely  than  as  "context"  and  "owner"?  In  any 
case,  what  is  "the  mind"  here  involved?  If  it  be  just  the  pen-ex- 
perience with  awareness  of  its  own  being  as  the  context,  it  does  not 
require  for  this  confext  any  part  of  "the  stream  of  thought"  that 
James  sometimes  identified  with  "the  human  mind."  Neverthe- 
less, it  is  the  precise  equivalent  of  what  James  called  "the  mind" 
in  an  extremely  important  passage  that  I  am  soon  to  quote. 

James,  in  his  book,  The  Meaning  of  Truth,  devotes  a  chapter  to 
"The  Function  of  Cognition."  He  starts  it  by  staging  a  drama 
that  in  every  virtual  respect  is  a  reproduction  of  that  performed 
in  expounding  his  doctrine  regarding  Consciousness.  The  new 
dramatis  personce  are  but  virtually  interchangeable  substitutes  for 
the  old,  or  at  least  appear  to  be,  until  new  questions  rise.  The  old 
"pen-experience"  becomes  first  an  algebraic  "q,"  then  a  concrete 
"paper-experience."  And  the  old  "second  experience"  or  "con- 
text" (whose  identity  puzzled  me)  at  least  seems  to  make  its  bow 
merely  under  a  new  alias,  ' '  a  feeling  of  q " :  at  first,  James  creates 
it  "in  a  little  universe,  all  by  itself";  then  remarking  that  "there 
can  be  no  '  feeling  of  q '  without  a  q  of  which  it  should  be  the  feeling, ' ' 
he  creates  the  q  that,  when  embodied,  becomes  "the  paper"  substitute 
for  the  "pen-experience"  in  its  original  immediacy  and  not  at  all 
conscious.  Thus  staged,  here  they  stand,  the  two  creations,  each  "in 
a  little  universe,  all  by  itself,"  already  for  the  play  to  begin! 

Presto!  Whether  the  "#"  or  the  "feeling"  pressed  the  button 
is  concealed.  But  somehow  "The  Function  of  Cognition"  presum- 
ably substituting  for  the  old  "act  of  addition"  or  " appropriative 
consciousness"  transpires.  The  two  creations,  "the  paper"  and  "the 
feeling,"  become  "one  identical  fact"  or  "one  experience"  which 
James  describes  as1  follows:  "The  paper  seen,  and  the  seeing  of  it 
are  only  two  names  for  one  identical  fact.  .  .  .  The  paper  is  in  the 
mind  and  the  mind  is  around  the  paper,  because  paper  and  mind  are 
only  two  names  given  later  to  the  one  experience.  .  .  .  To  know  im- 
mediately, therefore,  or  intuitively,  is  for  mental  content  and  object 
to  be  identical." 

This  drama  presumably  furnishes  a  conscious  mind  in  embryo; 
but  it  answers  none  of  our  questions  and  prompts  others.  Its  last 


676  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

sentence,  which  James  emphasized  by  italics,  unmistakably  implies 
that  unconscious  experiences  (like  those  of  the  pen  and  the  paper  be- 
fore awareness  was  added  to  them)  are  mental  contents,  and  are  not 
objects  of  consciousness  or  awareness.  But  contents  of  what?  From 
neither  drama  can  one  be  sure  that  James  conceived  such  unconscious 
experiences  to  be  constituents  of  any  mind  or  stream  of  any  sort.  And 
to  be  sure  regarding  what  he  conceived  them  to  be  contents  of,  one 
must  study  his  writings  more  widely. 

None  of  the  quotations  that  I  have  made  throws  any  convincing 
light  on  two  great  problems  involved  in  any  presumption  of  minds  of 
any  sort ;  namely,  the  problems  of  ' '  many  in  one, ' '  and  of  ' '  continu- 
ous existence."  And  in  our  hunt  for  what  James  conceived  uncon- 
scious experiences  to  be  contents  of,  let  us  first  examine  his  notorious 
difficulties  regarding  "many  in  one"! 

In  his  Psychology  and  elsewhere,  James  inveighed  violently 
against  "gluing"  mental  things  together,  for  example,  by  "associa- 
tion," in  pretended  constitution  of  that  unique  oneness  which  charac- 
terizes the  immediate  field  of  consciousness  of  any  mind.  Yet  James's 
method  of  enacting  this  oneness  seems  hardly  to  do  more  than  substi- 
tute the  word  "addition"  for  "association"  and  "gluing."  Never- 
theless, the  important  facts  for  my  present  purpose  are  that  James 
explicitly  insisted  upon  this  sort  of  unique  oneness  for  his  conscious 
minds  (such  as  of  which  he  declared,  "the  paper  is  in  the  mind  and 
the  mind  around  the  paper"),  but  quite  took  for  granted  an  equally 
unique  though  utterly  different  oneness  of  the  respective  unconscious 
pen  and  paper  experiences;  and  in  case  that  he  did  conceive  a  vast 
and  varied  manifold  of  likewise  unconscious  experiences  to  constitute 
any  "mind"  or  ff stream  of  thought"  only  parts  of  which  should, 
occasionally  and  in  successive  islands,  become  endowed  with  the 
unique  oneness  of  their  conscious  addition,  he  also  quite  took  for 
granted  whatever  sort  of  oneness  he  conceived  to  be  so  constituted 
by  that  generally  unconscious  "mind"  or  "stream,"  thus  leaving 
us  uncertain  as  to  how  he  conceived  the  contents  of  any  uncon- 
scious pen-  or  paper-experience  to  be  joined ;  as  to  how  he  conceived 
such  unconscious  experiences  to  be  joined  when  forming  any  mind 
or  stream ;  and  as  to  how  he  divided  his  "one  general  sort  of  stuff" 
among  "plural  minds,"  either  wholly,  or  with  an  incalculable  re- 
mainder not  in  any  mind. 

The  importance  of  these  facts,  within  James's  general  teachings, 
is  obscured  within  his  two  dramas,  partly  because  he  used  only  spacial 
experiences  in  expounding  them ;  whereas,  had  he  used  a  manifold  of 
sounds  in  place  of  a  pen,  or  of  a  rectangular  paper,  the  problem  of 
how  many  distinct  sounds  may  be  regarded  as  in  any  one  mind  or 
stream  rather  than  in  any  other,  save  as  the  result  of  some  consciously 


THE  COSMOLOGY  OF  WILLIAM  JAMES  677 

uniting  ' '  act, ' '  would  at  least  have  been  more  likely  to  occur  to  any- 
one who,  like  James,  had  renounced  all  but  empirical  explanations 
of  such  problems.  But  because  James's  q  algebraically  stood  as 
much  for  any  unconscious  manifold  of  sounds  not  displayed  spaci- 
ally  as  for  any  unconscious  manifold  of  colors  displayed  spacially, 
we  must  ask:  By  what  empirical  right  did  James  conceive  uncon- 
scious spacially  united  "paper  rectangles"  to  exist  at  all;  or  con- 
ceive numerically  distinct  "g's"  not  spacially  displayed  to  exist  in 
any  one  mind  or  stream  rather  than  in  any  other,  or  than  in  abso- 
lute separateness  in  no  mind? 

Moreover,  having  asked  this  pertinently  of  the  problem  of  "many 
in  one, ' '  there  remains  the  problem  of  ' '  continuous  existence. ' '  Did 
James  conceive  all  his  universal  stuff  to  exist  eternally  ?  Did  he  con- 
ceive the  beginning  and  the  end  of  whatever  mind  or  stream  he  did 
conceive  to  exist  simultaneously,  its  past  and  its  future  sections  as 
well  as  his  "specious  present"?  And  if  all  the  stream  did  not  exist 
simultaneously,  in  what  mind  did  James's  unconscious  things  exist; 
and  in  what  sense  did  their  "flow"  constitute  either  any  conscious  or 
any  unconscious  mind?  Naive  men,  rationalists,  and  followers  of 
"the  Absolute"  at  least  attempt  to  make  plain  how  questions  like 
these  are  to  be  answered.  But  as  nothing  in  all  James 's  writings  fur- 
nishes, sure  evidence  for  deciphering  his  undeniable  inspiration,  I  now 
follow  the  only  cue  I  can  discover  for  guessing  the  root  of  his  inveter- 
ate ambiguity — a  root,  perhaps,  of  which  he  was  never  aware. 

II 

Can  any  man  escape  from  his  environment,  wholly?  James  was 
born,  bred,  and  lived  in  an  environment  and  in  an  age  of  rationalism. 
My  cue  is  my  suspicion  that  James,  in  spite  of  his  utmost  endeavor, 
never  fully  escaped  from  rationalism. 

James's  prime  resolve  was  to  practise  empiricism  only.  But  to 
me  he  seems  never  to  have  escaped  many  habits  unwittingly  absorbed 
from  his  surroundings  and  readings.  Among  other  evidences  of  this 
he  seems  at  will  to  have  used  his  ' ' stuff ' '  quite  as  any  rationalist  uses 
"phenomena,"  used  his  "feelings  of  relations"  quite  as  any  follower 
of  Mr.  Bradley  uses  "inconceivable"  relations,  and  used  his  "experi- 
ences" quite  as  he  accused  Eoyce  of  using  "the  Absolute"  or  as  a 
"mere  reservoir  of  convenience." 

Boyce  "conveniently"  used  innumerable  phenomena  all  eternal!;/ 
"supported"  in  the  Absolute.  James  as  "conveniently"  used  in-- 
numerable "Berkeleyan"  and  "experienced"  things  all  eternally 
"existing"  somewhere.  But  though  James  renounced  both  "the  Ab- 
solute" and  "the  Naive  Man's  World,"  he  seems  blindly  to  have  felt 
no  need  of  stating  precisely  where,  how,  or  by  what  right  he  conceived 


678  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

convenient"  things  "to  exist,"  or  whether  in  some  particular 
mind  or  "ins  blau  hinein." 

Royce  used  innumerable  phenomena  all  unconscious  of  themselves 
and  severally  united  into  many  sorts  of  manifolds,  each  by  some 
"act"  of  "the  Absolute."  James  used  innumerable  "expe- 
riences" all  unconscious  of  themselves  and  severally  united  into 
many  sorts  of  manifolds,  unconscious  pens,  papers,  orchestrations, 
etc.  But  though  he  renounced  "the  Absolute"  and  resolved  to 
practise  empiricism  only,  he  seems  blindly  to  have  felt  no  need  of 
explaining  how  these  unconscious  manifolds  could  be  conceived  to 
be  united  spacially,  numerically,  or  at  all,  otherwise  than  occa- 
sionally by  some  uniquely  adding  and  consciousness-endowing 
"act"  of  some  empirical  "me"  or  "mind." 

Royce  used  phenomena  as  "universals";  one  served  for  all 
minds — literally  one  it  should  have  been,  since  nothing  (save 
"transcendental  egos"  and  "relations")  could  be  "plural"  or 
"different"  in  itself,  or  unless  "acted  upon"  by  some  ego.  James 
used  "experiences"  precisely  likewise  whenever  it  suited  him  to 
do  so.  In  explaining  How  Two  Minds  Know  The  Same  Thing  he 
just  conveniently  added  "the  same  thing"  to  each  mind,  where- 
upon it  became  known  as  "one  and  the  same  thing,"  or  as  "two 
different  things"  accordingly  as  some  "me"  "acted  upon"  the 
two  minds  in  exercise  of  some  "feeling  of  relation." 

Followers  of  Mr.  Bradley  use  his  "inconceivable"  relations  also 
as  "universals."  James  used  his  "feelings  of  relation"  likewise 
and  as  "inconceivably."  In  his  Psychology  and  elsewhere,  he 
declared  that  no  two  experiences  ever  are  the  same,  or  ever  are  in 
the  same  mind  twice,  or  ever  are  in  but  the  one  mind.  Neverthe- 
less, James  permitted  himself  at  will  to  transgress  all  these  declar- 
ations. Suppose  several  men  including  James  simultaneously  to 
have  seen  a  Berkeleyan  tiger  charge  from  its  farthest  visible  dis- 
tance to  an  immediate  foreground!  James  would  have  said  that 
"as  mental  content"  or  as  "things  in  themselves"  his  distant  ex- 
perience was  as  "different"  from  his  glorious-sheen-in-tawny-and- 
black  close-up  experience,  as  a  flyspeck  from  a  mountain  landscape 
or  a  county  fair.  Yet  in  successive  breaths  he  would  have  called 
the  flyspeck-tiger  and  the  close-up  tiger  "as  mental  object  or  Berke- 
leyan thing,"  now  "the  same,"  now  "different,"  now  "one,"  now 
"plural,"  now  "the  same  tiger  or  experience  in  different  minds," 
now  "different  manifolds  of  different  content  in  different  minds," 
and  in  this  last  he  merely  would  have  changed  "different"  to  "the 
same,"  if  occasion  suggested  it.  Here  we  recall  that  James  de- 
clared of  the  paper-experience  that  "paper  and  mind  are  only  two 
names  given  later  to  the  one  experience";  and  that  he  commonly 


THE  COSMOLOGY  OF  WILLIAM  JAMES  679 

declared  that  the  Dipper  Stars  of  the  Great  Bear  are  seven  "only 
when  counted."  And  if  James  had  been  asked  for  his  warrant  for 
all  this  sort  of  use  of  his  "feelings  of  relation,"  I  suspect  that  he 
would  have  replied  as  "conveniently"  as  Royce  or  any  other  ra- 
tionalist. 

James's  later  writings  are  replete  with,  seemingly,  every  con- 
ceivable "g,"  "feeling  of,"  and  "feeling  of  relation,"  and  with 
every  conceivable  "me"  to  feel  them  and  "own"  them  in  uniquely 
united  oneness.  They  provided  him  with  a  duplicate  supply  com- 
petent to  every  possible  known  thing  and  knowing  thing.  And 
with  this  more  than  'rationalistic  supply,  James's  problems  in  con- 
scious addition,  unconscious  division,  and  plural  cosmology  were 
easy.  He  had  but  to  clap  together  some  universal  "pen,"  some 
"feeling  of"  it,  plentiful  "feelings  of  relation,"  and  innumerable 
"me's"  for  his  universal  formula  of  pen-cognition  to  be  complete. 
If  it  happen  to  be  a  sort  of  pen  that  he  saw,  that  pricked  some 
blind  man's  finger,  that  some  babe  swallowed,  that  Roosevelt  took 
to  Africa,  and  that  Caesar  used  in  his  "still  sleeping"  past,  James 
had  but  to  add  so  many  feelings  of  "the  same"  and  of  "mine"  in 
order  to  make  five  "me's"  conscious  of  the  one  "universal,"  time- 
lessly  stuck  at  the  "common  intersection"  or  cross-roads  of  five 
"streams  of  thought"  or  "minds."  And  if  in  such  a  "quasi 
chaos"  of  feelings  of  "mine,"  "yours,"  "Roosevelt's,"  "out  to 
Africa,"  and  "back  to  Caesar"  should  rise  innumerable  feelings 
of  "if,"  "and,"  "but,"  and  "doubt"  regarding  who  is  who  and 
what  is  what,  there  was  always  at  hand  "in  the  rush  of  the  mind 
through  its  world  of  fringes  and  relations"  (James's  words)  still 
another  feeling — the  all-satisfying  feeling  that  "Whatever  a  man 
trowest  is  true." 

In  short,  James's  empiricism  is  one  that  can  make  all  the  furni- 
ture of  the  universe  unconsciously  exist  in  every  conceivable  mani- 
fold, both  in  innumerable  minds  simultaneously,  and  successively 
in  the  ever-varying  medleys  of  their  differently  ' '  flowing  streams ' ' ; 
can  make  them  all  "felt"  and  "felt"  in  every  conceivable  relation 
by  innumerably  "occurring"  and  conscious-endowing  "me's"  in 
each  of  the  innumerably  plural  "streams";  and  at  will  can  dump 
them  all  into  his  genetically  primitive  "quasi  chaos"  that  is  in- 
definitely conscious  or  unconscious,  that  evolves  by  no  definable 
order  of  logic,  of  biology,  or  of  nature,  and  that  is  neither  empiri- 
cal nor  rationalistic,  while  as  a  "reservoir  of  convenience"  it  is 
only  ignominiously  less  majestic  than  "the  Absolute." 

Nevertheless,  my  cue  has  led  me  neither  to  undervalue  James's 
work  nor  to  exaggerate  its  defects.  Simply  he  undertook  a  task 
impossible  for  any  one  man  or  even  any  one  generation  of  men  to 


680  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

complete.  The  Naive  Man  did  not  become  the  Rationalist  in  a 
day;  nor  will  the  Rationalist  become  the  Empiricist  in  a  day — 
perhaps  only  the  Rational  Empiricist,  ever.  James's  work  will  be 
lastingly  momentous  to  the  future  of  mankind,  however  it  be 
named.  And  the  highest  tribute  that  mankind  can  pay  to  his 
instinctively  penetrating  genius  is  now  to  make  his  prophetic  dark- 
ness clear,  revealing  the  difficulties  through  which  he  staggered 
toward  a  dawn  of  incomparable  promise. 

Ill 

James's  prime  intention  was  to  be  empirical;  and  if  my  review 
of  his  work  discovers  it  to  have  been  successful  wherever  he  suc- 
ceeded in  being  empirical,  and  to  have  failed  wherever  he  failed 
to  be  empirical,  these  discoveries  will  at  least  have  the  warrant  of 
his  premeditated  judgment  regarding  the  primary  requirement  of 
all  philosophic  procedure. 

James  began  with  unconscious  "stuff."  But  no  empiricist 
who  declares  that  "the  paper  seen  and  the  seeing  of  it  ...  are 
one  identical  fact"  can  discover  unconscious  stuff  in  his  own  field 
of  consciousness.  To  have  begun  empirically,  James  should  have 
begun  with  a  conscious  q.  Moreover,  had  he  done  this,  he  would 
have  needed  no  "act"  for  adding  awareness  to  the  q.  Also,  hav- 
ing created  a  typical  conscious  q  or  "stuff-mind"  in  a  universe  all 
by  itself,  it  could  have  remained  from  the  beginning  to  the  end  of 
eternity  absolutely  unchanged;  and  this  possibility  should  have 
warned  James  that  consciousness  is  not  likely  to  be  any  sort  of 
"act,"  and  that  no  conscious  stuff-mind  ever  needs  any  "occa- 
sional" endowment  of  consciousness.  Indeed,  in  any  absolutely 
unchanging  universe,  no  transpiring  act  of  any  sort  whatsoever 
could  be  possible.  Therefore,  no  empiricist  should  make  use  of 
any  "act"  whatsoever  until  he  presumes  to  explain  how  one  "con- 
scious whole"  is  continuously  succeeded  by  a  different  "conscious 
whole"  in  any  sort  of  "stream."  In  any  case,  we  discover  that 
neither  James's  unconscious  stuff,  nor  his  consciousness  endowing 
"acts  of  addition"  have  any  empirical  warrant. 

Having  wrongly  begun  his  empirical  task  with  unconscious 
stuff  and  rationalistic  "acts"  for  occasionally  endowing  it  with 
consciousness,  James  permitted  himself  to  conceive  his  stuff  to  con- 
stitute uniquely  united  unconscious  manifolds  without  need  of  any 
unifying  "acts,"  and  as  no  pure  rationalist  ever  would  do.  That 
is  to  say,  James  made  his  q  algebraic  of  every  sort  of  manifold  ever 
discovered  in  any  uniquely  united  field  of  consciousness.  Yet  in 
nothing  did  James  display  his  instinct  for  empiricism  more,  or 


THE  COSMOLOGY  OF  WILLIAM  JAMES  681 

more  crucially,  than  in  pertinaciously  insisting  on  the  absolutely 
unique  oneness  of  each  and  every  "conscious  whole." 

Moreover,  had  James  perceived  the  need  of  distinguishing 
plural  minds  in  a  universe  constituted  of  one  general  sort  of  stuff 
as  clearly  as  he  perceived  the  need  of  distinguishing  plural  egos 
within  the  Absolute,  he  would  have  perceived  that  a  conscious  q 
mind  constituted  by  any  manifold  of  stuff  uniquely  united  in  a 
"conscious  whole,"  once  clearly  conceived  to  be  the  ultimate  type 
of  all  egos,  minds  or  me's,  furnishes  precisely  the  distinction  of 
them,  one  from  another,  never  before  made  definitely  conceivable. 

In  the  precise  meaning  that  the  manifold  of  each  stuff-mind  is 
"one  conscious  whole,"  plural  stuff -minds  are  not  "one  conscious 
whole."  The  absolutely  unique  junction  of  stuff  in  one  conscious 
whole  is  the  indispensable  and  ultimate  distinction  of  a  stuff-mind; 
the  absolute  absence  of  any  such  junction  between  them  is  the  in- 
dispensable and  ultimate  distinction  of  plural  stuff-minds;  James's 
unconscious  stuff  had  no  empirically  warranted  junction  or  dis- 
junction; and  neither  any  unconscious  mind  nor  any  unconscious 
stuff  has  any  empirical  warrant. 

Every  abstract  prime,  causal  or  logical,  is  pure  algebra,  till 
"stuffed."  "Soul,"  "ego,"  "center  of  apperception,"  "energy," 
"unconscious  space,"  every  sort  of  "me,"  "thing,"  "act,"  and 
"relation"  is  pure  algebra,  till  "stuffed."  And  if  there  be  any- 
thing "Unknowable,"  these  unstuffed  things  should  have  been  the 
"  unknowables "  of  Kant  and  Spencer — not  the  stuff  that  in  a  con- 
scious whole  is  the  only  sort  of  "knowable"  of  which  any  "mind" 
is  ever  empirically  conscious.  This  is  what  James  blindly  struggled 
to  say,  but  perpetually  contradicted. 

James  also  insisted  pertinaciously  that  each  conscious  field  "  as  a 
whole ' '  is  continuously  followed  by  each  succeeding  field  "as  a 
whole."  But  had  he  not  conveniently  and  virtually  conceived  his 
conscious  stuff  and  things  to  exist  eternally,  his  simile  for  the  mind 
would  not  have  been  a  "stream  of  thought,"  but  a  movie-show — a 
movie-show  mind,  all  of  whose  past  contents  have  ceased  to  exist  ab- 
solutely, all  of  whose  future  contents  do  not  yet  exist,  and  whose  pres- 
ent field  is  absolutely  all  that  any  mind,  ego,  or  me,  ever  empirically 
is — a  movie-show  in  which  each  momentarily  existing  ' '  whole ' '  trans- 
forms absolutely  and  continuously  to  the  next  following  "whole." 

Such  a  mind  is  not  without  mysteries.  Conscious  existence  is  a 
mystery,  but  unconscious  existence  is  a  greater  and  added  mystery. 
Conscious  unity  of  any  manifold  is  a  mystery,  but  any  sort  of  united 
unconscious  manifold  is  a  greater  and  added  mystery — including  alike 
that  of  any  unconscious  "stream  of  thought"  and  that  of  any  un- 
conscious space.  Absolute  transformation  of  any  whole,  or  of  any 


682  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

part  of  any  whole,  is  a  mystery,  but  it  is  less  a  mystery  than  any  sort 
of  "gluing,"  either  by  unconscious  space  or  by  any  rationalistic 
"act."  The  continuity  of  this  absolute  transformation  is  a  mystery, 
but  it  is  less  a  mystery  than  either  an  eternal  atom,  or  any  "un- 
stuffed"  ego,  or  anything  that  is  always  both  "the  same"  and  "differ- 
ent" 

A  conscious  unity  of  manifold  stuff,  absolutely  and  continuously 
transforming!  This  is  the  typical  mind  that  James's  titanic  struggle 
reveals,  when  stripped  of  rationalistic  ambiguities.  Its  mysteries  are 
the  simplest  and  fewest  of  ultimate  mysteries ;  no  others  are  needed. 
It  suffices  for  his  "Plural  Universe,"  "all  of  one  general  sort 
of  stuff."  It  suffices  for  science,  without  the  added  mysteries  of 
"an  unconscious  spacial  plenum,"  and  without  ignoring  all  that 
psychology  and  philosophy  have  ever  accomplished.  It  suffices 
for  psychology,  without  any  multitudinous  and  insolvable  algebra  of 
unstuffed  "faculties,"  "acts,"  and  "relations."  And  it  suffices  for 
all  philosophy  or  cosmology,  without  any  ' '  reservoir  of  convenience ' ' 
filled  with  Unstuffed  Unknowables. 

IV 

But  how  can  any  such  Jamesesque  mind  know  any  other  such 
mind,  or  what  other  such  minds  of  various  species  constitute  the 
plural  Universe?  For  this  question,  as  for  all  exact  discussion  of 
cosmology  and  of  epistemology,  mutually  exclusive  definitions  of 
"conscious"  and  "know"  are  indispensable.  Therefore,  for  my  pres- 
ent writing,  I  dogmatically  declare  that  the  proper  meaning  of  each 
of  these  two  words  is  absolutely  unique,  and  different  from  that  of 
the  other.  Every  mind  is  conscious  of  its  present,  consciously 
united  self  and  never  is  conscious  of  anything  else.  Every  mind 
knows  other  things,  but  never  knows  its  present  self. 

I  have  spent  years  in  completing  for  publication  an  epistemology 
conforming  to  this  dogma.  But  for  present  writing,  I  simply  declare 
that  any  mind  knows  its  past,  knows  any  other  mind,  knows  any 
part  of  any  other  mind,  and  knows  the  species  of  any  other  mind  all 
in  one  general  way  that  has  two  modes,  instinct  or  intuition,  and 
reason  or  inference. 

James  refused  to  infer  that  the  atoms,  ether,  and  vast  plenum  of 
modern  physics  exist — "as  yet"  or  otherwise  than  as  "permanent 
possibilities"  and  "conceptually."  He  refused  to  infer  their  exist- 
ence even  in  any  guise  of  his  mental  stuff.  Nevertheless,  he  explic- 
itly declared  for  mental  genesis.  He  himself  suggested  that  spacial 
existence  has  some  sort  of  genesis  from  ' '  crudely  voluminous ' '  exist- 
ence. And  as  the  result  of  this  suggestion,  the  progressive  genesis  in 


TEE  COSMOLOGY  OF  WILLIAM  JAMES  683 

each  human  mind  of  homogeneous  undifferentiated  existence  or 
11  presentation, "  to  numerical  presentation  and  thence  to  spacial 
presentation  all  by  one  common  law  of  conditional  growth,  now 
stands  unchallenged,  save  by  human  inertia.  All  alike  are  warrants 
of  inference,  and  are  as  truthful  warrants  for  inferring  something, 
essentially  replacing  the  entire  plenum  of  present  physics,  as  for 
inferring  the  mind  of  one's  wife  or  son. 

James's  vision  of  the  human  mind  was  clearer  than  that  of  any 
previous  man.  But  his  vision  of  the  universe  was  densely  fogged 
by  his  rationalism.  His  type  of  universe,  like  that  of  every  ration- 
alist, is  'rooted  in  the  ancient  belief  that  "Man's  soul  is  the  center 
and  image  of  God's  purpose."  He,  like  Fechner,  conceived  the 
planets  to  be  godlike  minds ;  but  he  was  intolerant  of  existing  atoms, 
and  would  have  been  horrified  at  evolutionary  minds  that,  like  his 
"mind  around  the  paper,"  should  essentially  embrace  the  great  nebu- 
la and  vast  interstellar  spaces. 

But  why  should  any  man  any  longer  refuse  to  infer  something  in 
some  species  of  mind  from  the  entire  gamut  of  our  Berkeleyan  expe- 
riences? How  can  any  scientist  now  fail  to  do  this,  unless  to  be  a 
scientist  is  to  be  unmindful  of  all  that  psychology  and  philosophy 
have  accomplished?  And  how  can  any  psychologist  or  philosopher 
now  fail  to  do  this,  unless  to  be  a  psychologist  or  a  philosopher  is  to 
be  unmindful  of  all  that  science  has  accomplished  ? 

Previous  to  Berkeley,  all  men  and  all  animals  instinctively  lived 
by  this  sort  of  universal  inference,  and  doubtfully  could  have  evolved 
without  this  instinct.  It  has  the  warrant  of  the  entire  biologic  in- 
stinct of  the  ages.  And  its  abandonment  by  modern  rationalism  has 
no  other  warrant  than  Man's  sophisticated  exaltation  of  his  own 
image. 

Once  accept  James's  Plural  Universe  all  of  one  general  sort  of 
stuff,  and  the  Jamesesque  mind,  patiently  understood,  becomes  the 
sufficient  warrant  to  future  cosmologists  for  inferring  how  one  mind 
knows  any  other  mind,  what  species  of  minds  exist,  and  what  sort  of 
consciously  united  manifolds  constitute  each  of  these  species. 


James  did  more  for  solving  the  future  problems  of  mankind  than 
his  school,  let  alone  his  generation,  yet  appreciates.  The  only  ade- 
quate memorial  to  his  genius  can  be  to  complete  his  marvellously 
prophetic  vision. 

HERBERT  NICHOLS. 
BEOOKLINE,  MASS. 


•  >M          JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

THE  CONCEPT  OF  SENSATION 

WHILE  a  large  amount  of  excellent  research  work  has  been  done 
in  investigating  the  functioning  of  the  various  special  sensei, 
the  status  of  sensation  in  general  is  far  from  being  clear.  Its  various 
alleged  attributes,  in  terms  of  which  it  is  in  fact  defined — quality, 
intensity,  extension,  duration,  clearness,  order,  texture  and  the  like — 
are  not  well  defined.  Indeed,  there  seems  to  be  no  immediate  prospect 
of  securing  agreement  even  as  to  the  number  of  such  attributes.  So 
if  we  ask  what  sensation  itself  is,  no  clear  and  reliable  answer  ap- 
pears to  be  available,  and  the  whole  subject  is  characterized  by 
subjective  opinions  rather  than  objective  certainties.  For  structural 
psychology  at  any  rate,  this  is  a  serious  matter.  Indeed  it  would 
not  be  too  sweeping  to  say  that  the  whole  progress  of  the  science  is  in 
jeopardy.  For  instance,  the  theory  of  perception  is  left  without  a 
solid  basis,  a  situation  perhaps  particularly  obvious  when  we  con- 
sider the  numerous  attempted  explanations  of  the  perceptual  illu- 
sions whose  lack  of  finality  arises  from  their  seeking  to  analyze  these 
experiences  into  sensational  elements  whose  own  nature  is  not  clearly 
known.  A  breakdown  in  our  understanding  of  the  nature  of  sensa- 
tion inevitably  invalidates  a  large  part  of  structural  psychology. 

The  view  which  I  wish  to  propose  in  the  following  pages,  and 
which  I  think  can  be  made  a  consistent  part  of  a  constructive  psy- 
chological scheme,  is  that  by  sensation  we  mean  what  I  shall  call 
receptor  response.  In  a  moment  I  shall  explain  and  seek  to  justify 
the  use  of  this  term,  but  to  make  clear  what  I  mean,  let  us  apply 
this  suggested  characterization  of  sensation  to  one  or  two  of  the 
fairly  numerous  borderline  cases  which,  on  purely  introspective  evi- 
dence, it  is  difficult  to  classify  as  sensational  or  perceptual.  Is 
vocality,  for  example,  an  attribute  inherent  in  auditory  sensations, 
•or  is  it  something  superadded,  something  read  into  the  bare  data 
of  audition?  The  view  which  I  advocate  offers  us  a  perfectly  defi- 
nite systematic  answer:  vocality  is  sensational  if  it  arises  out  of 
specific  changes  in  the  receptor,  and  otherwise  not.  Or  again,  con- 
sider the  local  signs  of  visual  sensations.  Are  these  sensational  or 
not?  Again,  our  clean-cut  systematic  answer  is  that  they  are  if 
they  arise  out  of  some  specific  condition  in  the  visual  receptor,  and 
that  they  are  not  if  they  arise  out  of  conditions  in  the  centers  or  in 
other,  non-visual  receptors,  e.g.,  the  kinesthetic  receptors.  These 
instances  will  serve  to  show  my  meaning  when  I  define  sensation  as 
receptor  response. 

In  making  uso  of  the  term  receptor  response  I  am  employing  a  con- 
cept which  so  far  as  I  know  has  never  been  isolated  in  current  behavior- 
istic  discussii.ii--.  though  it  is  implied  in  them.  Perhaps  I  can  best  dem- 


THE  CONCEPT  OF  SENSATION  685 

onstrate  its  consistency  with  the  behavioristic  point  of  view  in  general 
by  reviewing  the  treatment  of  sensation  which  is  offered  by  the  so- 
called  "extreme"  behaviorists,  a  treatment  which  seems  to  me  radi- 
cally defective.  John  B.  Watson  proposes  in  effect  to  give  up  the  con- 
cept of  sensation  altogether  and  contends  that  all  those  differences 
which  structural  psychology  interprets  as  inherently  sensational  can 
be  dealt  with  as  differences  in  effector  response.  Rather  crudely 
put,  his  suggestion  would  be  that  a  difference  such  as  that  between 
red  and  green  depends  upon  the  fact  that  light  of  one  wave  length 
impinging  on  the  retina  causes  the  response  "red,"  while  light  of 
another  wave  length  causes  the  response  "green."  I  would  like  to 
call  attention  to  two  closely  related  difficulties  to  this  account.  First, 
it  hardly  seems  to  meet  the  facts.  Vague  and  unsatisfactory  as  the 
structuralist  view  of  sensation  differences  may  be — and  I  for  my 
part  must  indorse  Watson's  criticism  of  it — it  does  at  least  recognize 
sensations  as  ultimate  and  irreducible  qualitative  differences,  and  so 
far  at  least  it  seems  sound.  That  there  are  such  differences  in  our 
mental  life,  differences  which  can  not  be  resolved  into  anything  else, 
seems  a  plain  fact  to  which  no  general  prejudice  against  the  intro- 
spective method  ought  to  blind  us.  Thus  it  is  that  the  attempt  to  inter- 
pret what  the  structuralist  calls  sensation  differences  in  terms  of  differ- 
ences in  effector  action  appears  to  be  an  over  simplification  at  the  ex- 
pense of  reality.  The  second  objection  is  that  Watson  operates  with  a 
conception  of  response  that  is  far  too  narrow — which  is,  indeed,  the 
ground  of  his  failure  to  deal  adequately  with  the  facts  of  mental  life. 
For  him  response  is  nothing  but  end-result.  Now  light  of  different 
wave  lengths  might  set  up  completely  different  retinal  processes  or 
completely  different  neurograms  without  registering  in  different  end- 
results.  If  this  were  the  case,  still  on  Watson 's  theory,  the  organism 
would  remain  unaware  of  the  difference  in  color,  simply  because  the 
difference  failed  to  register  in  its  muscles  and  glands,  surely  a  par- 
adoxical result. 

Evidently  what  is  required  is  a  more  inclusive  definition  of  re- 
sponse. Why  should  objective  psychology,  which  sets  out  to  offer 
explanations  in  terms  of  organic  behavior,  limit  itself  to  explanations 
in  terms  of  effector  action  only?  There  seems  no  reason  whatever 
for  dividing  the  effector-receptor  circuits  at  some  arbitrarily  chosen 
point,  whether  just  back  of  the  effectors  or  elsewhere,  and  saying 
that  everything  on  one  side  of  the  line  is  response  while  everything 
on  the  other  side  is  not.  It  is  no  plea  in  favor  of  hypothetical  brain 
schemes  to  urge  that  objective  psychology  must  take  account  of  all 
and  not  a  mere  part  of  the  facts  of  organic  life.  The  critical  point, 
the  point  where  essential  differences  actually  arise,  is  not  between 
receptor  tissue  and  neural  tissue,  nor  between  neural  tissue  and 


686  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

effector  tissue,  but  between  the  organism  as  a  whole  and  its  environ- 
ment. All  that  the  organism  does  on  the  cues  of  external  stimulation 
is  in  the  nature  of  response.  As  I  have  argued  more  fully  elsewhere 1 
we  can  not  separate  out  from  behavior  either  central  processes  or 
receptor  processes,  and  must  think  of  response  as  any  bodily  change 
brought  about  by  external  stimulation. 

Clearly  the  immediate  consequence  of  this  is  the  consistency  and 
tenability  of  the  concept  of  receptor  response,  though  we  must  recog- 
nize it  under  certain  conditions  which  will  be  discussed  later.  But 
in  any  case  it  is  a  tenable  notion.  And,  furthermore,  it  is  of  great 
value  in  clearing  up  the  whole  doctrine  of  sensation  differences,  for 
it  makes  possible  an  objective  account  which  recognizes  the  very  fact 
which  Watson  tends  to  ignore  and  which  the  structuralists  take  into 
account,  the  fact  that  what  are  called  sensation  differences  are  ulti- 
mate and  can  not  be  explained  in  terms  of  anything  else. 

I  turn  now  to  a  more  detailed  consideration  of  the  view  of  sensa- 
tion as  receptor  response  as  it  applies  to  a  number  of  closely  related 
psychological  problems. 

1.  I  begin  by  considering  the  nature  and  status  of  so-called  simple 
unitary  sensations.  That  this  is  a  point  at  which  introspective  psy- 
chology finds  itself  in  difficulties  is  evident  from  the  widely  varying 
estimates  offered  of  the  total  number  of  possible  sensations.  Such 
lack  of  agreement  can  be  symptomatic  of  nothing  but  ambiguity  in 
the  conception  of  simple  sensation  itself.  Can  the  theory  here  advo- 
cated throw  any  light  upon  this  matter  ? 

Here  at  once  we  come  upon  what  seems  at  first  sight  the  most 
paradoxical  consequence  of  the  view  that  sensations  are  nothing  but 
receptor  responses.  For  it  is  obvious  that  unless  the  afferent  and 
central  fibres  are  in  working  order,  changes  in  the  sense  organ  do 
not  register  at  all  in  mental  life.  Take  an  individual  whose  optic 
nerve  has  been  damaged  without  any  injury  to  his  eyes.  Light  will 
set  up  the  regular  retinal  changes,  as  far  as  we  know.  That  is, 
there  can  be  receptor  responses,  which  on  our  definition  are  sensa- 
tions. But  he  will  still  be  blind.  Now  this  result  is  due  not  to  a 
fault  in  the  theory,  but  to  the  ambiguity  of  the  word  sensation. 
Let  us  keep  constantly  in  mind  its  identical  equivalence,  for  us,  to 
receptor  response,  and  the  paradox  is  no  longer  very  troublesome. 
When  we  say  that  a  change  in  the  sense  organ  must  set  up  changes 
in  the  central  mechanism  in  order  to  ' '  register, ' '  what  do  we  mean  ? 
We  mean  that  the  receptor  response  becomes  integrated  as  an  ele- 
ment in  the  total  behavior  of  the  organism,  while  if  the  neurones 
are  so  affected  that  it  does  not ' '  register, ' '  we  mean  that  it  does  not 

•    i"The  Stimulus  Response  Relation,"  Psychol.  Eev.,  Vol.  29,  No.  2,  p.  152. 


THE  CONCEPT  OF  SENSATION  687 

become  so  integrated.  For  us  the  prime  work  of  the  whole  nervous 
system  must  be  integrative.  Now  behavior  psychology  operates  in 
terms  of  total  response.  This,  indeed,  is  its  difference  from  physi- 
ology. Thus  our  conclusion  is  that  unintegrated  receptor  responses 
— simple  sensations  in  isolation,  to  use  the  traditional  terminology 
— are  entirely  beyond  the  realm  of  psychology.  The  point  is  not 
that  as  a  result  of  education  and  sophistication  we  always  add  to 
and  interpret  our  simple  sensations.  Kather  it  is  that  for  the 
normal  individual,  with  his  receptors  in  structural  and  functional 
contact  with  the  neural  mechanism,  isolated  simple  sensations  are 
impossible,  and  that  when  they  do  occur  owing  to  accident  or  injury, 
they  play  absolutely  no  part  in  total  behavior  or  mental  life,  and 
are  mere  physiological  curiosities. 

Here,  of  course,  we  come  upon  the  explanation  of  the  difficulty 
found  by  introspection  in  separating  out  and  counting  simple  sensa- 
tions. The  actual  material  open  to  introspective  survey  contains 
no  free  simple  sensations.  It  does  not  even  contain  complexes  made 
up  of  nothing  but  simple  sensations.  It  consists  of  sensational  ele- 
ments, to  be  sure,  but  these  are  organized  into  very  elaborate  com- 
plexes, and  bound  up  with  non-sensational  elements.  So  it  is  that 
all  structuralistic  attempts  to  show  how  mental  functions  can  be 
analyzed  down  into  series  and  constructs  of  simple  sensations  are 
bound  to  fail  simply  because  the  underlying  organic  conditions  of 
mental  life  are  such  that  mental  functions,  to  exist  and  occur  at  all. 
must  involve  more  than  receptor  responses.  Simple  sensations,  or 
isolated  and  unitary  receptor  responses  exist,  and  exhibit  ultimate 
and  irreducible  differences,  but  they  do  not  exist  in  isolation,  and 
the  psychologist  can  not  deal  with  them  by  themselves. 

2.  This  leads  me  to  the  problem  of  perception,  and  more  specif- 
ically of  the  perception  of  space  and  time.  Perceptual  knowledge 
is  defined  as  consisting  of  complexes  made  up  of  sensations  and 
nothing  but  sensations.  But  if  we  regard  sensations  as  receptor 
responses  it  becomes  clear  that  such  complexes  in  fact  never  occur 
in  mental  life.  We  might,  it  is  true,  have  a  number  of  responses 
occurring  simultaneously.  But  this  in  itself  would  not  constitute 
perception.  It  is  necessary  that  the  various  incoming  impulses  be 
integrated  at  the  centers,  and  if  we  look  at  the  matter  from  the 
point  of  view  here  advocated  it  is  evident  that  this  condition  de- 
stroys the  purely  sensational  character  of  the  complexes  which  re- 
sult. The  bringing  together  of  various  incoming  impulses,  as  we 
have  in  effect  indicated,  must  be  interpreted  to  mean  their  integra- 
tion into  the  warp  and  woof  of  total  behavior.  That  is,  the  organic 
conditions  which  the  structuralist  rightly  thinks  of  as  necessary 


688  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

for  the  occurrence  of  perception,  more  correctly  understood  imply 
that  we  never  have  pure  perception  at  all,  that  the  alleged  sensation 
complexes  are  in  reality  much  more  complicated  and  heterogenous, 
consisting  of  both  sensational  and  non-sensational  elements. 

The  point  is  especially  clear  when  we  consider  our  alleged  per- 
ceptual knowledge  of  space  and  time,  which  is  supposed  to  be  built 
up  out  of  visual,  tactual,  kinesthetic,  somatic  and  other  sensations. 
But  the  idea  that  sensations  are  self-sufficient  self-existent  atoms 
of  knowledge  which  contain  the  primal  stuff  from  which  is  elabo- 
rated our  awareness  of  the  space-time  manifold  and  which  can  be 
combined  into  various  patterns  by  the  central  nervous  system  is  not 
tenable.  On  the  one  hand,  a  mere  sensation  in  and  of  itself  is  not 
knowledge  at  all,  for  it  plays  no  part  in  mental  life.  And  on  the 
other  hand,  the  central  mechanism  does  a  great  deal  more  than 
recombine  the  data  from  the  receptors.  It  consolidates  receptor  re- 
sponses with  mental  life  in  general.  There  emerges  here  a  sugges- 
tion of  the  right  direction  in  which  to  look  for  constructive  solu- 
tions of  the  problems  with  which  the  structuralist  attempts  to  deal 
in  the  psychology  of  perception.  For  it  appears  that  our  awareness 
of  space  and  time  is  not  something  special  and  definite,  a  special 
kind  or  texture  of  sensations,  but  that  it  is  simply  our  skill  in  mak- 
ing gross  motor  and  bodily  adjustments  to  the  environment. 

The  general  conclusion  to  which  we  are  driven  here  is  that  in 
spite  of  the  fact  that  we  can  retain  sensation  in  a  strictly  behavior- 
istic  scheme,  we  can  not  retain  perception.  We  agree  with  the 
structuralist  that  sensations  are  ultimate  and  irreducible  differ- 
ences. But  we  do  not  in  the  least  agree  that  they  can  be  regarded 
as  self -existent  atomic  entities  out  of  which  more  complex  knowl- 
edge structures  can  be  built.  As  receptor  responses  they  have  no 
meaning  in  mental  life  except  when  integrated  with  behavior  as  a 
whole  by  the  action  of  the  central  mechanism,  and  in  this  case  they 
become  consolidated  with  non-sensational  elements  from  which  they 
can  never  be  disentangled. 

3.  Finally  let  us  consider  the  status  of  imagery  and  the  alleged 
imaginal  content  of  thought.  I  shall  not  raise  the  question  as  to 
whether  imagery  exists  or  not,  for  to  deny  it  as  certain  behaviorists 
do  seems  to  me  a  flagrant  contravention  of  plain  fact  in  the  interests 
of  a  theory.  The  matter  that  is  of  interest  here  is  its  relation  to  sen- 
sation. 

Let  us  assume  that  imagery  is  constituted  by  activity  in  the  cen- 
ters. To  what  extent,  if  at  all,  may  we  expect  to  be  able  to  correlate 
it  to  sensation  ?  First  and  foremost  there  is  every  reason  for  believ- 
ing a  priori  that  we  ought  to  be  able  to  assimilate  imagery  to  the 


THE  CONCEPT  OF  SENSATION  689 

various  special  senses,  so  that  we  can  speak  intelligibly  of  visual, 
auditory,  kinesthetic  and  tactile  imagery,  and  so  forth.  The  mere 
fact  of  the  functional  localization  of  the  central  mechanism  seems 
decisive  on  this  point.  A  visual  image  will  arise  out  of  activity  in 
the  visual  areas;  an  auditory  image  out  of  activity  in  the  auditory 
areas,  and  so  forth.  But  beyond  this  we  may  not  be  able  to  go,  for 
1  there  is  a  profound  organic  and  functional  difference  between  imagery 
and  sensation,  the  latter  being  constituted  by  change  in  the  recep- 
tors and  the  former  by  change  in  the  centers.  Here  I  think  we  are 
at  the  source  of  introspective  difficulties  with  imagery,  for  attempts 
to  work  out  any  thoroughgoing  correlation  between  the  characteris- 
tics of  imagery  and  sensation  seem  to  be  erroneous  in  principle. 
The  more  constructive  attempt  would  be  not  to  analyze  it  into 
sensationalistic  equivalents  which  it  does  not  and  can  not  possess, 
but  rather  to  deal  with  it  in  terms  of  its  influence  on  general  be- 
havior. 

The  consideration  of  imagery  suggests  a  mention  of  the  question 
of  the  alleged  imaginal  content  of  thought.  The  most  serious  system- 
atic argument  against  imageless  thought  is  that  the  doctrine  seems  to 
involve  us  in  the  paradox  that  thinking  is  a  sort  of  vacuum,  a  process 
where  nothing  happens  because  there  is  nothing  there,  but  which 
still  gives  us  tangible  results.  Now  from  the  introspective  point  of 
view  the  only  concrete  reals  in  mental  life  are  sensations  and  sensa- 
tion-like images.  Hence  we  derive  the  view  that  all  thought  proceeds 
by  means  of  images.  Obviously,  however,  the  concept  of  sensation 
which  I  have  advocated  forbids  us  to  deal  with  thought  as  a  succes- 
sion of  sensation-like  contents.  But  it  does  more  than  this.  It  sup- 
plies an  adequate  alternative  to  the  theory  of  imageless  thought  by 
showing  how  we  may  regard  thinking  as  a  series  of  concrete  happen- 
ings, though  not  a  series  of  contents.  We  agree  with  Watson  here 
that  thought  is  a  sort  of  'action,  though  we  do  not  necessarily  limit 
it  to  laryngeal  work.  Sensations  and  images  are  actions  too,  and 
thought  may  or  may  not  involve  either  of  them  together  with  other 
types  of  activity  as  well. 

I  close  with  a  word  on  the  systematic  significance  of  the  considera- 
tions here  worked  out.  It  will  be  observed  that  I  have  used  a  number 
of  ambiguous  expressions  throughout  this  entire  discussion.  I  have 
spoken  of  sensations  "registering"  and  of  "mental  life,"  terms 
which  suggest  the  introspective  point  of  view.  This  has  been  done 
quite  deliberately  in  the  belief  that  it  simply  does  not  matter.  With 
introspection  as  such,  we  can,  I  think,  have  no  quarrel,  for  science 
can  not  afford  to  repudiate  any  method  which  may  lead  to  the  dis- 
covery of  any  modicum  of  fact.  What  we  do  quarrel  with,  however, 
is  the  imposition  of  ill-defined  theories  upon  introspective  data. 


690  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

In  particular,  psychology  must  avoid  two  extremes.  On  the  one 
hand,  an  objective  scheme  is  under  no  obligation  to  find  equivalents 
for  all  structuralistic  conceptions.  A  behaviorism  which  is  nothing 
but  a  forced  translation  of  structuralistic  theory  is  nominal  only. 
Objective  psychology  must  work  out  its  own  system  in  its  own  way, 
and  that  system  may  or  may  not  have  points  of  contact  with  others 
that  ha.ve  been  proposed.  As  we  have  specifically  seen  here,  the 
theory  of  perception  can  have  no  place  in  such  a  system,  though  of 
course  the  facts  which  the  theory  of  perception  attempts  to  explain 
must  be  considered.  On  the  other  hand,  we  must  not  ruthlessly  re- 
ject all  the  notions  of  structural  psychology  merely  because  we  find 
the  introspective  method  irritating  in  certain  cases.  Specifically  we 
have  seen  that  sensation  has  an  objective  meaning.  To  be  of  any 
value,  behaviorism  must  stand  on  its  own  feet  and  work  out  its  own 
conclusions  without  prejudice  either  for  or  against  any  other  scheme. 

JAMES  L.  MUBSELL. 
LAKE  ERIE  COLLEGE. 


IS  CONSCIOUSNESS  PHYSICAL? 

IN  his  recent  article,  "The  New  Materialism,"1  Professor  Pratt 
has  seen  fit  to  include  me  among  the  materialists.  To  this  I 
have  no  objection  so  long  as  the  classification  does  not  shut  out  from 
view  what  I  regard  as  novel  in  my  outlook.  Historical  forms  of 
materialism  have  always  been  weak  in  their  epistemology  and  in  their 
handling  of  the  categories.  For  this  reason  I  have  preferred  the 
more  general  term  "naturalism"  which  is,  as  it  were,  still  in  the 
making. 

But  when  I  come  to  the  content  of  his  exposition  and  criticism, 
I  discover  that  he  has  partially  failed  to  see  the  implications  of  the 
epistemology  which  we  supposedly  have  in  common.  I  hasten,  there- 
fore, to  make  my  reply  in  order  that  others  may  not  be  misled.  My 
argument  is  necessarily  complex  and  involves  some  measure  of 
subtlety.  Were  this  not  the  case,  I  would  hardly  expect  it  to  offer 
a  solution  of  such  an  age-old  puzzle  as  that  of  consciousness  and 
brain.  I  shall  summarize  my  position  and  bring  out  its  principles, 
and  then  I  shall  answer  Professor  Pratt 's  objections. 

I 

The  essentials  of  my  position  can,  I  think,  be  summarized  under 
the  following  six  points: 

1.  Consciousness  is  a  term  far  the  compresence  of  contents  which 
i  This  JOURNAL,  Vol.  XIX,  No.  13. 


IS  CONSCIOUSNESS  PHYSICAL?  691 

each  of  us  has  as  his  field  of  experience.  Particular  elements  of  this 
field  are  called  states  of  consciousness  or  psychical.  This  compresent 
complex  has  an  empirical  structure  characterized  by  the  distinction 
between  the  self  and  what  is  presented  to  the  self.  Naturally,  though 
unfortunately,  consciousness  is  also  used  as  a  term  for  awareness, 
which  is  the  felt  presence  of  contents  to  the  self's  inspection,  a  de- 
velopment within  consciousness  as  a  compresence  of  contents.  In 
what  follows,  we  are  concerned  primarily  with  the  nature  and  exis- 
tential locus  of  the  elements  of  this  complex.  Are  these  elements 
physical  ? 

2.  The  elements  of  this  complex  are  given,  experienced  or  intuited 
in  a  way  impossible  for  physical  things.    Physical  things  are  objects 
of  perception  and  knowledge  but  this  knowledge  is  mediated  by 
contents,  that  is,  these  objects  are  affirmed  and  interpreted  in  terms 
of  these  contents.    In  ordinary  perception,  this  is  done  uncritically; 
in  science,  information  about  physical  systems  in  terms  of  position, 
mass,  energy,  structure  and  behavior  is  worked  out.    My  argument 
demands  that  the  exact  nature  of  this  knowledge  be  understood. 

3.  The  contrast  between  the  elements  of  consciousness  and  phys- 
ical things  has  a  threefold  origin:  (a)  epistemological,  (b)  categor- 
ical, and  (c)  theological. 

When  I  say  that  a  sense-datum  of  mine  is  not  physical,  I  may 
mean  that  it  is  not  a  part  of  the  particular  physical  thing  which  I 
know  by  means  of  it  and  which  I  may  first  have  identified  it  with. 
To  call  it  psychical  in  this  connection  is  to  assert  that  it  is  subjective 
and  bound  up  with  my  organism,  that  it  is  not  out  there  where  the 
thing  is.  This  contrast  tells  us  nothing  about  the  relation  between 
the  sense-datum  and  the  percipient  organism.  It  does  not  imply  a 
difference  of  substance,  a  metaphysical  dualism.  Since  the  datum 
is  compresent  with  images,  meanings,  and  feelings,  the  whole  complex 
is  thought  of  as  alike  in  status  and  nature.  Its  existential  locus  is  a 
problem. 

But  when  I  say  that  a  sensation  or  image  or  feeling  is  not  phys- 
ical, I  may  have  another  context,  the  categorical.  I  mean  that  the 
categories  of  my  knowledge  of  the  physical  world  do  not  seem  to 
apply  to  these  entities.  I  do  not  know  them  in  the  same  way  that  I 
know  physical  systems  nor  do  my  categories  cover  them.  This  is  the 
categorical  or  metaphysical  setting  of  the  problem.  ButVhat  does 
it  signify  ?  Simply  what  the  first  did,  viz.,  that  these  are  subjective 
elements  internal  to  the  organism  and  not  themselves  total  physical 
things.  The  relation  can  not  be  one  of  simple  equivalence.  But  are 
there  not  other  possibilities?  Must  we  not  explore  the  relation  of 
whole  and  part  ?  It  is  this  that  materialism  always  tried  to  do,  but 


692  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

clumsily,  because  it  had  no  clear  epistemology  and  no  logical  acute- 
ness. 

The  third  motive  to  the  contrast  between  consciousness  and  the 
physical  was  the  theological.  This  was  external  and  irrelevant  and 
produced  the  disastrous  metaphysical  dualisms  of  the  past.  Con- 
sciousness was  made  a  function  of  a  soul  distinct  from  the  body.  I 
can  not  find  any  empirical  motive  for  this  solution  in  the  facts  them- 
selves. Yet  I  can  not  help  feeling  that  it  is  in  the  background  of 
Professor  Pratt 's  mind. 

4.  Now  as  a  critical  realist,  Professor  Pratt  should  have  appre- 
ciated the  emphasis  which  I  put  upon  the  two  kinds  of  knowledge 
as  the  key  to  the  solution.    In  fact,  I  called  my  solution  the  double- 
knowledge  view  of  the  mind-body  problem.     We  have  knowledge 
about  the  brain  in  terms  of  the  physical  categories  and  we  inspect 
the  contents  of  consciousness  or  else  feel  them.     This  difference  in 
kind  of  knowledge  should,  alone,  make  us  aware  that  simple  equiva- 
lence is  too  facile  a  solution. 

5.  "What  is  another  possibility?    May  not  a  content  of  our  con- 
sciousness be  a  peculiar  part  of  the  functioning  brain?     And  here 
again  we  are  assisted  by  our  epistemology.    If  the  relation  of  whole 
and  part  is  thought  of  in  terms  of  our  knowledge  of  the  physical 
world,  it  takes  the  form  of  spatial  whole  and  part,  as  a  pea  is  in  a 
pod  or  an  atom  in  a  molecule.    But  consciousness  is  not  thus  known. 
Hence  it  should  not  be  so  thought.    What  other  relation  of  whole 
and  part  can  we  conceive  ?    It  seems  to  me  that  the  relation  of  struc- 
ture or  quality  to  that  which  is  structured  or  qualitied  gives  us  a 
suggestion.    The  case  is  by  its  very  terms  unique.    Consciousness  is 
something  given ;  it  is  a  reality,  while  we  have  only  knowledge  of  the 
physical  world,  no  participation  in  its  very  stuff  unless  consciousness 
be  a  partial  participation.    But  we  have  seen  that  a  simple  identifica- 
tion of  an  equivalence  sort  is  out  of  the  question.     To  express  the 
situation,  I  have  called  the  psychical  a  variant.    It  is  a  variant  as 
structure  is  a  variant,  but  it  is  other  than  structure  because  it  is  a 
flash  of  the  content  of  the  brain.     Thus  I  hold  consciousness  to  be 
physical  in  the  sense  that  it  is  an  internal  character  of  the  function- 
ing brain,  though  it  is  not  a  complete  physical  thing  to  be  known 
externally  by  the  sense-data  it  arouses. 

I  maintain  that  this  interpretation  satisfies  the  epistemological 
and  categorical  motives.  And  if  critical  realism  is  to  appeal  to  con- 
temporary thought  it  must  have  some  such  solution  of  the  status 
and  locus  of  the  psychical. 

6.  But  is  consciousness  efficacious?     Is  interactionism  with  its 
dualistic  implications  the  only  possible  kind  of  efficacy?    The  prin- 
ciple I  have  adopted  is  that  consciousness  must  have  an  efficacy  cor- 


IS  CONSCIOUSNESS  PHYSICAL?  693 

respondent  to  its  nature.  Interactionism  is  not  true  to  this  prin- 
ciple. It  wants  to  give  consciousness  powers  which  it  does  not  ap- 
pear to  possess  or  to  turn  the  efficacy  over  to  a  soul  created  for  the 
purpose.  I  need  not  enlarge  upon  the  difficulties  interactionism  has 
always  faced. 

What  can  the  inactive  contents  of  consciousness  do?  They  can 
guide  and  give  warning.  How  guide?  Not  by  controlling  neural 
processes  from  outside  in  a  dynamic,  pushful  way,  but  by  being  the 
focus  of  the  neural  process  and  thus  assisting  discrimination. 
Frankly,  I  can  not  comprehend  adjustment  to  complex  situations 
without  such  an  instrument  for  summing  up  and  comparing  factors. 
When  I  reason  I  think  of  my  brain  as  making  an  adjustment  by 
means  of  its  abilities,  using  as  intrinsic  summaries  and  guides  the 
contents  which  I  am  aware  of  using. 

To  this  suggestion  I  know  what  the  reply  will  be.  We  are  so 
accustomed  to  think  of  the  brain  in  terms  of  the  information  furnished 
by  physical  science  that  we  mistake  its  reach  and  suppose  that  it 
exhausts  the  brain.  The  truth  is  that  the  brain  should  be  thought 
of  as  the  brain-mind.  We  impoverish  nature  by  identifying  it  with 
the  skeleton  which  science  deciphers.  The  brain  has  a  "content  of 
being"  which  physical  science  can  not  intuit  and  which  it  tends  to 
ignore.  A  psychical  content  is  a  qualitative  dimension  of  the  ac- 
tive brain-mind  integral  with  it. 

II 

Let  me  now  reply  to  Professor  Pratt. 

His  first  objection  is  that  I  have  two  variants  and  have  the  prob- 
lem of  bringing  these  into  relation.  Now,  so  far  as  I  can  make  out, 
his  belief  that  I  accept  two  variants,  consciousness  and  brain  activity, 
is  due  to  his  misunderstanding  of  the  categorical  motive  which  I  solve 
by  the  double  knowledge.  As  classes  thought  about  they  are  distin- 
guished, but  do  they  exist  in  this  fashion?  The  brain  is  known  in 
two  ways:  one  is  knowledge  about  and  the  other  is  participation. 
But  the  reach  of  these  two  ways  is  not  equivalent;  hence  the  two 
logical  classes.  But,  existentially,  consciousness  is  a  participant  in 
and  part  of  the  neural  process.  Suppose  Professor  Pratt  granted  this 
situation,  he  would  see  that  the  categorical  contrast  would  follow.  I 
conclude  that  his  dialectic  is  misplaced. 

But  why  do  I  not  call  consciousness  a  form  of  energy  ?  This  is  the 
only  way  out  of  the  difficulty  that  Professor  Pratt  can  think  of.  My 
reply  is  that  energy  as  a  category  of  science  is  a  term  for  a  quantita- 
tive measurement  of  the  power  to  do  work.  Here  again  we  are  con- 
fronted by  the  double  knowledge  of  the  brain.  To  call  consciousness 
which  we  immediately  experience  and  participate  in  a  form  of  energy 


694  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

is  to  mix  knowledge  with  reality.  Since  I  identify  brain  and  mind,  I 
am  willing  to  speak  of  neural  or  mental  energy.  I  am  willing  to 
speak  of  consciousness  as  a  qualitative  ingredient  in  the  discharge 
of  neural  energy.  But  to  speak  of  consciousness  as  a  form  of  energy 
is  to  me  rather  meaningless  and  betrays  the  sort  of  outlook  which 
used  to  speak  of  consciousness  as  a  mode  of  motion.  That  things 
move  is  knowledge  about  them.  That  they  are  active  in  a  measur- 
able way  is  knowledge  about  them.  I  fear  that  Professor  Pratt 
wants  me  to  be  as  naive  in  my  epistemology  and  handling  of  the 
categories  as  the  older  materialists. 

One  final  point:  "Professor  Sellars  does  not  seem  to  realize  that 
the  ultimate  difficulty  of  materialism  lies  not  in  the  kind  of  physical 
laws  which  it  sets  in  absolute  control  of  mind  and  human  behavior, 
but  in  setting  any  physical  laws  in  absolute  control."  But  laws  are 
our  human  formulations  of  how  things  behave.  Laws  do  not  control 
things ;  they  control  themselves.  And  when  I  recognize  with  behavior- 
ism that  mental  laws  are  physical  laws,  that  is,  that  we  can  know  the 
mind  by  its  behavior  and  that  the  laws  of  introspective  psychology 
only  supplement  these,  I  no  longer  have  the  objection  to  physical 
laws ;  I  no  longer  think  of  them  as  laws  of  mechanics  alone.  But  if 
Professor  Pratt  wants  the  mind  to  be  lawless? 

I  conclude  that  I  do  not  believe  that  I  am  guilty  of  the  traditional 
blunders  of  materialism  and  am  not  impaled  on  both  horns  of  Pro- 
fessor Pratt 's  dilemma.  Consciousness  is  physical  and  extended, 
but  is  not  a  spatial  part  of  the  brain. 

R.  W.  SELLARS. 
UNIVERSITY  or  MICHIGAN. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 

La  Mentalite  Primitive.    L.  LEVY-BRUHL.    Paris :  Alcan.    1922.    Pp. 

iii  -f  537. 
La  Religion  et  la  Foi.     HENRI  DELACROIX.     Paris:  Alcan.     1922. 

Pp.  xii  +  462. 

This  very  interesting  volume  continues  the  author's  earlier  work 
in  the  same  field,  Les  Fonctions  Mentales  dans  les  Societes  Infcri- 
eures.  In  the  present  work,  M.  Levy-Bruhl  is  primarily  interested 
in  the  attitude  of  so-called  "primitive"  people  toward  what  we  are 
accustomed  to  call  causality,  and  in  showing  that  what  has  made 
"primitive"  folk  seem  so  often  incorrigibly  ignorant,  superstitious, 
and  fantastic  is  their  entire  confidence  in  their  own  metaphysical 
explanations. 

The  work  is  what  works  in  this  field  necessarily  are,  an  extensive 
collection  of  the  observations  and  reports  of  travellers,  explorers,  and 


BOOK  REVIEWS  695 

missionaries,  not  cited  in  support  of  an  unduly  definite  thesis,  but 
left  to  speak  for  themselves,  though  classified  for  the  sake  of  order 
under  the  chapter  headings  of  a  dozen  chapters.  M.  Levy-Bruhl  is 
no  doubt  right  in  believing  that  the  manners  and  practises  of  "primi- 
tive" people  have  been  greatly  misunderstood  because  observers  of 
them  have  naturally  enough  interpreted  these  in  terms  of  their  own 
categories.  The  great  difference  between  uncorrupted  tribesmen  and 
ourselves  to  which  the  author  calls  attention  is,  as  I  have  said,  in  the 
matter  of  causal  explanations.  It  is  like  the  difference  between  the 
explanations  of  an  epidemic  by  a  sincere  and  consistent  Christian 
and  by  a  well-informed  materialist; — the  former  may  attribute  the 
epidemic  to  the  will  of  God  while  the  latter  attributes  it  to  polluted 
drinking  water.  Obviously  if  God  wills  it  he  may  work  His  will  by 
means  of  drinking  water  or  of  anything  else ;  it  is  idle  to  be  curious 
about  secondary  causes  when  the  primary  one  is  uncontrollable. 
What  we  call  physical  causation  is  something  the  "primitive"  never 
thinks  of,  or  to  which  he  is  very  indifferent. 

The  person  who  has  what  we  call  intelligence  lives  in  a  world  in 
which  he  believes  the  near  and  the  immediate  to  depend  on  the  more 
remote  both  in  time  and  space.  What  is  important  belongs  to  the 
world  of  causes ;  they  it  is  that  must  be  respected ;  it  is  with  reference 
to  them  that  behavior  must  be  orientated.  But  these  causes  are 
physical  causes  of  like  nature  with  their  physical  effects.  The 
"primitive"  lives,  as  we  have  been  often  told,  in  a  totally  different 
world ;  his  world  of  causes  is  a  world  of  invisible  occult  powers,  the 
irritable  and  irresponsible  dead,  more  or  less  undeveloped  gods,  a 
mysterious  causality  resident  in  omens,  the  magical  and  terrifying 
power  for  evil  inhabiting  the  sorcerer,  perhaps  quite  unknown  to  him. 
These  are  the  real  causes,  and  they  manifest  themselves  in  all  sorts  of 
ways.  Details  of  physical  causality  are  irrelevant.  "Accidents"  do 
not  exist.  Events  in  any  way  unusual  reveal  the  operations  of  dan- 
gerous powers,  and  lead  the  natives  concerned  to  extravagant  and 
destructive  methods  of  defense.  Under  these  circumstances,  natives 
can  not  learn  from  experience.  Crocodiles  and  leopards  are  believed 
to  be  naturally  harmless;  if  a  native  is  attacked,  it  is  because  a 
sorcerer  has  made  the  leopard  or  the  crocodile  his  instrument.  The 
problem  is  to  discover  the  sorcerer  as  a  modern  sanitary  engineer 
would  look  for  a  source  of  contagion.  Where  a  human  enterprise 
succeeds,  it  is  probably  not  by  virtue  of  experience,  skill,  and  per- 
sistence, but  because  of  an  effective  "medicine."  An  enemy  can  be 
defeated  not  by  greater  courage  and  better  tactics,  but  by  using  a 
stronger  "medicine"  than  his  opponent  can  use.  Some  natives  are 
slow  to  learn  to  use  firearms  because  they  will  not  take  aim,  and  be- 
cause they  have  no  conception  of  the  possible  range :  the  bullet  pur- 


696  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

sues  the  flying  game  and  is  bound  to  catch  it.  People  may  be  an- 
swerable for  what  they  have  done  in  a  dream,  or  for  what  they  have 
wished  either  dreaming  or  awake ;  the  dream  deed  is  a  real  deed  and 
the  wish  is  a  real  cause.  The  Creek  Indians  planned  to  strike  a  mortal 
blow  at  the  Blackfeet.  Before  starting  on  their  campaign  they 
practised  every  sort  of  magic  to  make  sure  of  success.  It  was  decided 
to  put  a  blindfolded  young  Indian  girl  at  the  head  of  the  army  to 
guide  it.  Thus  they  set  out,  going  one  day  toward  the  north,  the 
next  toward  the  south  or  west,  for  the  war  manitou  was  supposed  to 
be  leading  them  (p.  372,  quoted  from  P.  J.  de  Sonet  S.J.,  Voyages 
dans  I'Amcrique  septentrionale,  pp.  150-152).  White  men,  on  their 
first  arrival,  are  supposed  to  be  the  dead  returning,  and  the  goods 
they  bring  with  them  are  made  by  other  dead  at  the  bottom  of  the 
sea.  Dreams  are  adventures  of  the  "soul"  or  revelations  from  the 
occult  powers.  Natives  are  quite  ready  to  prove  their  innocence  by 
the  ordeal  of  poison.  They  believe  unquestioningly  that  the  ordeal 
can  be  depended  upon  while  they  know  that  the  testing  of  their 
fellow  tribesmen  can  not  (p.  245).  The  truth  is,  they  know  noth- 
ing of  the  physical  action  of  poison.  Such  illustrations  of  what  looks 
like  spontaneous  and  innate  supernaturalism  could  be  continued  in- 
definitely. 

A  reader  wonders,  of  course,  whether  the  vocabularies  of  the  ob- 
servers really  translate  the  native  terms,  and  M.  Levy-Bruhl  puts 
us  on  our  guard.  If  the  natives  misunderstand  the  missionaries,  the 
missionaries  are  likely  to  be  ill  qualified  to  understand  the  natives. 
M.  Levy-Bruhl  pleads  for  better  qualifications  in  this  respect.  The 
"primitive"  races  are  rapidly  disappearing  or  becoming  corrupted 
and  diseased. 

If  the  history  of  supernatural  religion  has  been  a  tremendous 
factor  in  the  history  of  edifying  metaphysics,  studies  like  this  one 
ought  not  to  escape  the  notice  of  ' '  philosophers. ' '  Those  races  that 
have  had  a  history  emerged,  presumably,  from  the  stage  of  these 
peoples  without  history,  and  our  theories  about  "reality,"  our  devout 
epistemology  and  even,  sometimes,  our  theories  of  logic  are  lyric  with 
the  call  of  the  "mentalite  primitive." 

We  do  not,  as  a  rule,  speak  of  the  "faith"  of  primitive  folk  in 
their  gods,  their  magic,  and  their  dead;  the  word  faith  is  likely 
to  be  used  for  belief  in  the  face  of  difficulties  that  might  be 
acknowledged.  This  conscious  "belief,"  existing  perhaps  as  an 
orthodoxy  side  by  side  with  disbelief,  is,  though  M.  Delacroix  does 
not  say  so,  an  attenuation  of  the  entirely  naive  supernaturalism  of 
the  more  nearly  primitive  collective  imagination,  and  that  curious 
and  unwavering  orthodoxy  supplies  perfect  examples  of  la  foi.  M. 
Delacroix  writes,  however,  of  faith  as  it  is  documented  in  the  con- 


BOOK  REVIEWS  697 

text  of  more  or  less  awakened  and  professional  criticism.  La  Re- 
ligion et  la  Foi  is  a  work  of  great  erudition,  and  more  than  one 
reader  may  feel  himself  almost  continually  in  the  atmosphere  of 
definitions,  apologetics  and  of  learned  controversy.  All  of  it  is 
intended,  however,  to  illustrate  stages  and  qualities  of  faith.  "For 
faith  is  the  primary  religious  fact  for  the  psychology  that  studies 
the  religion  of  religious  souls.  Every  religion  announces  that  by 
faith  we  reach  realities  independent  of  the  individual;  but  every 
religion  admits  also  that  by  faith  we  establish  contact  with  these 
realities. 

"We  propose  to  try  to  describe  the  elementary  forms  of  faith, 
by  which  I  mean  the  distinct  and  ultimate  attitudes  which  this 
complex  term  denotes.  Psychological  analysis  shows  that  there  are 
different  ways  of  believing;  we  can  distinguish  rational  belief  in- 
clining to  scientific  certainty ;  emotional  belief,  based  on  needs  and 
attitudes,  and  conferring  a  singular  value  upon  its  objects;  faith 
resting  on  authority  and  hearsay  and  based  on  the  power  of  opin- 
ion or  of  institutions.  These  three  general  forms  of  faith  present 
themselves  and  this  classification  imposes  itself,  though  only  as  a 
schema"  (p.  ix).  Faith  in  its  primitive  form  is  la  foi  implicite, 
really  "the  faith  of  authority,  the  power  of  the  religious  environ- 
ment, the  pressure  of  society  upon  the  individual"  (p.  1).  Naive 
faith  shared  by  all  or  nearly  all  leads  to  cult,  and  faith  institu- 
tionalized demands  dogma  and  creates  it,  something  which  when 
made  self-consistent  becomes  a  system  of  theology.  "With  dogma 
comes  the  distinction  between  truth  and  error  with  the  resulting  ap- 
peal to  criticism,  leading  to  la  foi  raisonante.  Its  great  age  was  the 
"middle  age" — but  criticism  was  always  faith,  and  made  from  the 
inside,  not  from  the  outside.  Formality  and  authority  of  dogma- 
tism leads  to  a  romantic  reaction  in  the  forms  of  foi  confiance, 
vague  and  sentimental  but  free  and  individualistic,  faith  in  what 
eludes  definition.  When  this  becomes  aigu  there  is  certitude  mys- 
tique. 

There  follows  prophetic  inspiration,  fanaticism,  conversion,  out- 
side the  faith  and  la  foi  creatrice.  Religions  are  collective  things, 
and  group  excitement  and  effervescence  contribute  to  the  forma- 
tion of  religions.  But  behind  society  in  effervescence  is  society 
itself.  But  there  must  be  also  an  imaginative  conception  of  "the 
world,"  something  not  recognized  as  a  dream  but  accepted  as  hav- 
ing objective  validity.  Here  are  what  M.  Delacroix  calls  three 
principles,  the  product  of  which  is  the  power  which  excels  (de- 
posse)  both  in  subjectivity  and  objectivity  (p.  423).  "For  civil- 
ized men,  nature  is  not  divine.  It  is  greater  than  we  are,  but  we 
are  also  greater  than  it.  ...  But  nature  becomes  sacred  again  when 


698  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  esthetic  vision  frees  it  from  this  limitation."  Faith,  an  energy 
of  the  "spirit"  generates  its  objects  and  the  dogmas  about  them, 
and  these,  of  course,  react  on  the  faith  that  wrought  them. 

It  is  not  an  easy  book  to  read  and  it  is  less  easy  to  give  an  ac- 
count of  it.  The  reader  gets  certainly  a  sense  of  the  great  com- 
plexity of  the  subject  when  presented  in  the  setting  of  its  own 
literature.  The  bibliography  is  very  interesting. 

W.  T.  BUSH. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

SCIENTIA.  Vol.  XXXII,  No.  127-11.  Stellar  Distances  and  Stel- 
lar Motions:  W.  8.  Adams.  Vitalisme  ou  physico-chimisme.  Ipme 
Partie :  La  loi  d  'option  de  la  vie :  H.  Guilleminot.  La  contribution 
des  differents  peuples  aux  progres  de  la  science  economique :  A.  Loria. 
La  question  sociale:  L 'abolition  du  salariat:  G.  D.  H.  Cole. 

JOURNAL  DE  PSYCHOLOGIE.  XIXe  Annee,  No.  8.  Quelques  mots 
sur  la  psychologic  de  la  mathematique  pure :  Ph.  Chaslin.  Genese  de 
Tart  figure. — I.  La  phase  preliminaire  du  dessin  enfantin:  G.  H. 
Luquet.  Notes  et  Documents:  Une  amoureuse  de  pretre:  J.  Seglas. 
Nouvel  exemple  d  'evalaution  du  temps  par  un  schizophrene :  J.  Vin- 
chon  et  Monestier.  L'interet  psychologique  des  theories  de  la  rela- 
tivite :  M .  Boll. 

PHILOSOPHICAL  REVIEW.  Vol.  XXXI,  6.  Philosophy  in  France, 
1921:  A.  Lalande.  Anticipations  of  Kant's  Refutation  of  Sensation- 
alism: G.  C.  Bussey.  Three  Witnesses  against  Behaviorism:  J.  C. 
Gregory.  Discussion :  7  -f-  5  =  12 :  B.  Bosanquet.  The  Interpreta- 
tion of  Heraclitus:  T.  de  Laguna.  Awareness  and  Behaviorism: 
H.  C.  Warren. 

JOURNAL  OF  EDUCATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  XIII,  No.  8.  The 
Limits  Set  to  Educational  Achievement  by  Limited  Intelligence: 
M.  V.  Cobb.  The  Problem  of  Group  Intelligence  Tests  for  Very 
Young  Children:  R.  Pintner  and  B.  V.  Cunningham.  A  New  Tim- 
ing Device  for  "Work  Limit"  Group  Tests:  B.  W.  Robinson.  The 
Effectiveness  of  Oral  Versus  Silent  Reading  in  the  Initial  Memoria- 
tion  of  Poems :  C.  Woody.  The  Constancy  of  Intelligence  Quotients : 
E.  A.  Lincoln.  A  Report  on  the  Correlation  of  Psychological  Tests 
with  Academic  and  Manual  Subjects:  I.  Glenn.  The  Effect  of  the 
Study  of  Latin  on  Ability  to  Define  Words :  A.  R.  GUlUand. 

Bradley,  F.  H. :  The  Principles  of  Logic.  Second  Edition  Re- 
vised with  Commentary  and  Terminal  Essays.  Two  volumes.  New 
York :  Oxford  University  Press,  American  Branch.  1922.  xxviii  -f- 
738  pp.  $9.35. 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  699 

Ogburn,  William  Fielding :  Social  Change  with  Respect  to  Culture 
and  Original  Nature.  New  York :  B.  W.  Huebsch,  Inc.  1922.  365 
pp.  $2.00. 

Poppovich,  Nikola  M. :  Die  Lehre  vom  Diskreten  Raum  in  der 
Neueren  Philosophic.  Vienna  and  Leipzig:  Wilhelm  Braumiiller. 
1922.  89  pp. 

NOTES  AND  NEWS 

We  quote  the  following  from  an  article  on  "Art  and  Science" 
printed  in  the  Literary  Supplement  of  The  London  Times,  November 
2,  1922. 

' '  So  it  is  also  with  the  biological-psychological  method.  That  has 
value  only  when  employed  in  a  negative  way,  to  explain  failure  in 
art  and  error  in  aesthetic  experience,  not  art  itself  nor  true  esthetic 
experience.  At  present  it  is  often  employed  so  perversely,  and  with 
results  so  monstrous,  as  to  provoke  a  general  impatience  of  all  psy- 
chology; but  this  perversity  comes  of  an  arrogant  ignorance  of  the 
first  principles  of  aesthetic.  If  they  can  be  grasped  by  the  psycholo- 
gist, his  science  may  remove  obstructions  to  the  experience  and  even 
to  the  production  of  works  of  art. 

So  long  as  he  tells  us  that  all  art  is  an  unconscious  expression  of 
the  sexual  instinct,  he  tells  us  nothing  that  is  of  any  value  to  us.  He 
asserts  merely  that  something  is  happening  in  a  dark,  unknown 
region,  the  result  of  which,  when  it  reaches  the  light,  is  a  work  of  art. 
But,  as  everything  else  which  reaches  the  light  is  also,  according  to 
him,  a  result  of  the  same  cause  working  in  darkness,  we  are  left  with 
a  general  and  unconvincing  statement  about  everything.  Yet  this 
statement,  if  it  were  confined  to  certain  kinds  of  failure  in  art,  might 
help  us  to  understand  them.  For  it  is  probable  that  failures  in  art 
have  causes  in  the  unconscious ;  and  psychology  may  in  time  be  able 
to  discover  these  causes  and  the  connection  between  them  and  their 
effects  with  precision.  Thus,  the  unconscious  working  of  the  sexual 
instinct  may  be  the  cause  of  many  failures  in  art — for  instance,  of 
the  forbidding  sentimentality  of  some  religious  pictures.  This  re- 
volts instead  of  charming  us,  because  we  are  aware  of  something  in 
the  picture  other  than  what  the  artist  himself  consciously  intends. 
The  furtive  appetite  which  peeps  through  this  mask  of  devotion  is 
trying  to  infect  us  by  false  pretences ;  and  so,  unless  we  wish  to  share 
the  appetite,  we  refuse  to  be  moved  by  the  devotion  and  are  troubled 
and  disgusted  by  a  lack  of  unanimity  in  the  artist's  mind.  It  is  as 
if  he  were  not  quite  sane,  as  if  something  said  under  the  influence 
of  that  religious  drug  betrayed  not  a  self,  but  an  instinct  destroying 
the  unity  of  the  self.  Behind  all  this  show  of  the  artist  and  the 
devotee  there  is  a  monkey,  and  a  sentimental  monkey  is  something 


700  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

not  to  be  endured.  But  there  may  be  a  sentimental  monkey  lurking 
in  us,  too ;  in  which  case  we  shall  like  to  be  deceived  by  the  show  of 
devotion.  While  our  appetites  are  furtively  tickled,  we,  too,  shall 
believe  that  we  are  experiencing  a  religious  emotion.  Hence  the 
long  popularity  of  that  Magdalen  of  Titian's  who,  as  Euskin  said, 
looks  as  if  she  hoped  to  get  to  heaven  by  dint  of  her  personal  charms. 
But  there  is  all  the  difference  in  the  world  between  this  am- 
biguous concealment,  or  betrayal,  of  appetite  and  those  great  and 
simple  works  of  art  which  are  openly  concerned  with  sex.  Sex,  for 
instance,  is  the  theme  of  Coreggio's  Antiope,  not  its  secret  preoc- 
cupation. We  scent  nothing  in  that  picture  other  than  what  the 
painter  consciously  intends.  He  was  unanimous  when  he  conceived 
and  executed  it,  and  we  are  unanimous  and  untroubled  in  our  ex- 
perience of  it.  Further,  in  this  case,  and  in  all  great  works  of  art 
where  sex  is  the  theme,  it  seems  to  be  only  a  way  into  that  state 
of  being  which  all  great  art,  no  matter  what  its  theme,  creates.  In 
a  moment  we  are  beyond  the  subject,  beyond  all  those  frank  allure- 
ments of  beautiful  flesh,  in  the  paradise  of  which  Coreggio  was 
really  dreaming.  It  is  like  love  music  in  which  the  passion  is  freed 
from  its  object  and  the  love  lost  in  the  beauty  of  the  music.  By 
this  power  of  escape  all  great  art  may  be  known,  and,  so  far  from 
being  an  unconscious  expression  of  sex,  it  consciously  uses  sex,  like 
all  other  human  passions  and  concrete  things,  as  a  way  into  the 
Holy  of  Holies." 


VOL.  XIX.,  No.  26  DECEMBER  21,  1922  "^  ' 


THE  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


THE  EMERGENT  THEORY  OF  MIND 

MY  purpose  in  this  article  is  to  discuss  the  bearing  of  the  new 
theories  of  mind  upon  the  old  and  tantalizing  mind-body 
problem.  Recent  writers  do  not  seem  to  appreciate  how  the  problem 
has  been  shifted,  nor  how  completely  the  old  classical  solutions  have 
been  superseded.  I  think  that  in  the  future  we  shall  not  continue 
to  hear  much  about  interactionism,  parallelism,  epiphenomenalism, 
double-aspectism,  etc.,  except  as  interesting  historical  theories.  It 
remains,  however,  to  inquire  much  more  carefully  and  thoroughly 
than  I  can  in  this  brief  paper,  whether  the  emergent  theory  will 
be  adequate  to  cover  the  facts. 

It  is  my  belief  that  more  progress  has  been  made  in  the  past 
fifteen  years  in  coming  to  an  understanding  of  the  real  nature  of 
mind  than  in  all  the  centuries  since  Aristotle.  We  are,  indeed, 
coming  back  somewhat  to  his  view,  which  was  that  the  mind  is  the 
use,  perfection,  entelechy  of  the  body.  We  are  accustomed  to  hear 
about  the  points  of  difference  between  the  Neo-Realists,  the  Pragma- 
tists,  the  Freudians,  and  the  Behaviorists,  but  the  points  of  agree- 
ment are  more  significant.  These  schools  pretty  well  agree  in  re- 
garding mind  as  adaptive  behavior,  as  specific  response,  as  selective 
control;  more  exactly,  as  that  integration  of  vital  processes  which 
enables  an  organism  to  respond  as  a  unit  to  a  new  situation 
in  such  a  way  as  to  conserve  and  enhance  its  well-being.  Perhaps 
the  Freudians  and  some  of  the  Pragmatists  will  hardly  accept  this 
definition  without  qualification,  the  qualification  being  that  the  mind 
is  this  and  something  more — something  sui  generis,  something  new 
and  distinctive,  something  unique  and  creative.  With  this  qualifica- 
tion I  should  heartily  agree,  if  it  is  interpreted  pluralistically  and 
not  dualistically.  If,  however,  we  accept  this  definition  of  mind  as 
a  working  basis,  with  or  without  the  above  qualification,  it  is  inter- 
esting to  see  how  it  transforms  and  illumines  the  old  and  vexatious 
mind-body  problem,  which  in  times  past  has  come  so  near  driving 
some  of  us  crazy. 

In  defining  the  mind  as  that  organization  of  vital  processes  which 
makes  adaptive  behavior  possible,  it  is  mind  that  I  am  speaking 
of  and  not  consciousness.  Endless  confusion  and  misunderstanding 
would  have  been  avoided,  if  psychologists  and  philosophers  had 

701 


702  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

steadfastly  used  the  word  "mind"  to  denote  this  kind  of  behavior, 
this  sum  of  capacities,  and  not  the  word  "consciousness."  It  was 
most  unfortunate  that  in  the  last  decades  of  the  last  century,  when 
suspicion  began  to  attach  to  the  words  "soul"  and  "mind,"  psy- 
chologists fixed  upon  the  word  "consciousness"  to  stand  for  the 
psychical  life  in  general.  James  tried  to  put  a  stop  to  this  in  his 
celebrated  essay  but  he  did  not  seem  to  understand  clearly  the  rela- 
tion between  consciousness  and  mind.  In  recent  years  this  relation 
is  becoming  clear.1  I  shall  refer  presently  to  consciousness  in  its 
relation  to  the  body,  but  at  present  I  am  speaking  not  of  conscious- 
ness but  of  mind. 

It  is,  therefore,  with  a  decided  feeling  of  relief  or  even  of  eman- 
cipation that  we  discover  that  the  new  conception  of  mind  sets  us 
free  from  all  the  old  so-called  "solutions"  of  the  mind-body  prob- 
lem, from  interactionism,  from  parallelism,  from  epiphenomenalism, 
from  the  double-aspect  theory,  from  subjectivism,  and  from  material- 
ism. I  believe  these  "isms"  have  been  superseded.  So  also  probably 
has  the  expression  theory,  the  transmission  theory,  and  the  instru- 
ment theory.  The  brain  is  not  the  instrument  of  the  mind.  Rather 
the  brain  is  the  instrument  by  means  of  which  nature  achieves  the 
mind.  Mind  and  body  do  not  interact,  as  interactionism  and  dualism 
teach.  The  mind  is  not  a  form  of  the  mechanical  interplay  of  atoms, 
as  materialism  teaches.  The  body  is  not  a  phenomenon  or  appear- 
ance or  externalization  of  mind,  as  idealism  teaches.  Mind  and 
body  are  not  parallel  as  psychophysical  parallelism  teaches.  Neither 
are  they  two  sides  or  aspects  of  the  same  reality,  as  the  double- 
aspect  theory  teaches.  You  can  not  represent  the  relation  of  mind 
and  body  by  any  system  of  parallel  lines,  whether  merely  parallel, 
interconnected,  or  correlated  with  a  third  line,  nor  by  two  lines 
one  of  which  is  the  shadow  of  the  other.  Mind  is  something  which 
the  body  achieves,  or  which  nature  achieves  by  means  of  the  body. 
If  you  must  have  a  diagram,  the  ladder  will  be  better  than  the  paral- 
lel bars.  When  nature  achieves  the  molecule,  the  atom  ceases  to  be 
the  thing  of  primary  importance,  worth,  or  even  of  reality.  When 
nature  achieves  the  cell,  the  molecule  is  eclipsed.  When  the  organ- 
ism is  achieved,  the  cell  is  eclipsed.  When  mind  is  achieved,  the 
body  is  eclipsed.  Mind  is  a  new  reality,  gained,  achieved,  won.  It 
is,  in  Aristotelian  phrase,  the  form  of  the  body. 

i  Witness  the  rather  strong  language  used  by  Bertrand  Russell  in  his  book, 
The  Analysis  of  Mind,  p.  40.  "It  is  therefore  natural  to  suppose  that,  what- 
ever may  be  the  correct  definition  of  '  consciousness, ' '  consciousness '  is  not  the  es- 
sence of  life  or  mind.  In  the  following  lectures,  accordingly,  this  term  will  dis- 
appear until  we  have  dealt  with  words,  when  it  will  reSmerge  as  mainly  a  trivial 
and  unimportant  outcome  of  linguistic  habits." 


THE  EMERGENT  THEORY  OF  MIND  703 

Evidently,  if  we  want  a  name  for  this  new  notion  of  the  rela- 
tion of  mind  to  body,  we  may  call  it  the  emergent  theory.2  Mind 
emerges  from  the  body.  The  theory  of  levels  has  taken  the  place 
of  parallelism,  interactionism,  and  the  double-aspect  view.  It  is 
hard  to  say  which  of  these  theories  was  the  most  unsatisfactory  and 
the  escape  from  them  is  wholesome.  All  the  dualistic  theories  were 
unconvincing.  There  is  no  magic  about  the  number  two.  Nature 
having  achieved  two,  goes  on  to  three  and  four.  The  monistic 
theories  were  little  better,  although,  if  mind  be  the  supreme  reality, 
there  is  a  sense  of  the  word  " reality,"  which  admits  of  a  monistic 
interpretation,  a  monism  of  value  perhaps.  But  the  pluralistic  view 
of  reality  is  most  satisfactory.  Mind  is  real,  consciousness  is  real, 
body  is  real,  and  so  are  many  other  things. 

.  But,  some  reader  will  say,  the  mind-body  problem  can  not  be  dis- 
posed of  so  easily — in  this  high-handed  manner.  Mental  processes 
seem  to  be  correlated  with  bodily  processes.  With  every  mental 
image,  perception,  etc.,  some  neural  process  is  correlated.  Well, 
from  our  point  of  view,  they  are  not  correlated  and  there  is  no  dual- 
ity about  it,  nor  are  they  two  sides  or  aspects  of  the  same  reality. 
What  happens  is  that  we  have  a  series  of  vital  processes,  which,  when 
integrated  or  organized,  exhibit  capacities  that  we  call  mental  or 
psychical.  When  they  reach  the  point  of  attaining  to  that  kind  of 
activity  which  we  call  intelligent  control,  we  no  longer  speak  of 
them  as  vital  or  neural  processes,  but  as  psychical.  We  are  up  on 
a  new  level,  among  new  realities,  in  a  new  atmosphere,  dealing  with 
new  things,  having  their  own  laws  and  peculiarities.  Mind  has 
emerged  from  matter.  The  spiritual  has  emerged  from  the  physical. 
After  long  centuries  of  misuse  the  word  spirit  gains  a  definite  and 
profitable  meaning.  It  means  the  level  of  the  psychical  as  viewed 
from  the  standpoint  of  value. 

Thus  far,  I  think,  the  way  is  clear  and  the  emergent  theory 
seems  to  satisfy  the  conditions.  But  we  are  not  through  with  our 
troubles.  The  mind-body  problem  is  more  difficult  than  this.  There 
are  still  two  "waves"  to  be  met  and,  if  possible,  surmounted.  We 
can  not  evade  the  fact  of  consciousness  and  consciousness  is  not 
the  same  thing  as  mind.  Behaviorism,  as  a  new  method  of  advanc- 
ing the  science  of  psychology,  is  a  wholesome  discipline,  but  the 
psychologist  can  not  ignore  the  reality  known  as  consciousness, — at 
any  rate  the  student  of  philosophy  can  not.  Whatever  modern 
theory  of  consciousness  we  adopt,  the  "cross-section"  theory,  the 
"relational"  theory,  the  "independent  variable"  theory,  the  "new 

2  S.  Alexander,  who  has  made  the  emergent  theory  familiar  to  us,  says  that 
Lloyd  Morgan  and  George  Henry  Lewes  had  previously  used  the  term.  Compare 
his  Space,  Time  and  Deity,  Vol.  II,  p.  14. 


704  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

dimension  of  reality"  theory,  the  "something  adventitious  to  psy- 
chic states"  theory,  the  psychologist  has  consciousness  on  his  hands, 
if  not  in  his  head,  and  willy-nilly  must  do  something  with  it. 

I  have,  of  course,  no  intention  of  discussing  the  problem  of  con- 
sciousness here.  I  am  only  raising  the  question  whether  the  emer- 
gent theory  can  be  made  to  cover  it,  whether  it  is  simply  intelligent 
behavior  that  emerges  from  the  neural  level,  or  whether  conscious- 
ness may  emerge.  If  not,  then  is  consciousness  something  which  is 
parallel  with  the  neural  processes,  or  is  it  another  aspect  of  the 
neural  processes,  or  does  it  interact  with  them?  I  am  tired  of 
these  words  and  do  not  believe  that  any  of  them  apply  to  the  case 
in  hand,  although  there  are  greater  difficulties  here  than  in  the  case 
of  mind,  as  I  have  been  discussing  it.  Let  us  say  that  consciousness 
is  simply  the  relationship  between  the  mind  as  perceiving  and  the 
thing  perceived.  The  percipient  mind  is  acted  upon  and  responds 
to  the  thing  or  object,  and  this  sort  of  togetherness  is  what  we  mean 
by  consciousness  in  its  simplest  form.  Awareness  is  another  word 
for  the  same  thing  in  the  simple  form  of  it  here  described.  The 
mind-body  problem  simply  does  not  enter  into  the  matter  at  all. 
We  are  dealing  with  a  relationship  between  the  mind  as  a  real 
thing  and  the  object  as  another  real  thing,  but  the  first  term  in  this 
relationship,  namely,  the  mind,  has  emerged  from  the  body;  for, 
when  the  brain  has  attained  to  that  degree  of  integration  in  which 
behavior  of  this  kind  takes  place,  that  is,  adaptive,  selective  behavior, 
we  no  longer  call  it  neural  or  bodily,  but  psychical.  If,  however, 
anyone  should  prefer  to  speak  of  the  organism  or  the  brain  as  acting 
in  this  way,  that  is,  if  anyone  wishes  to  consider  the  brain  as  the 
percipient  subject,  why  then,  consciousness  as  before  would  be  the 
relationship  between  the  percipient  organism  and  the  object  per- 
ceived. In  either  case  consciousness,  as  a  special  kind  of  relation,  is 
something  real,  something  wholly  immaterial,  something  other  than 
and  much  narrower  than  the  mind,  and  something  related  to  the 
body  quite  otherwise  than  indicated  by  any  of  the  old  terms,  paral- 
lelism, interactionism,  double-aspect,  etc. 

But  the  word  consciousness,  as  it  is  used  in  everyday  speech, 
usually  means  something  more  than  mere  awareness.  It  approaches 
the  meaning  of  self -consciousness.  It  implies  not  merely  a  relation 
between  the  percipient  subject  and  the  perceived  thing,  but  a 
relation  between  the  present  and  the  past  history  of  the  subject. 
It  implies  that  the  whole  situation  takes  the  form  of  a  connected 
story.  But  so  far  as  the  bearing  upon  the  mind-body  problem  is 
concerned,  this  new  richness  of  the  word  "consciousness"  makes 
no  difference.  The  relationship  which  I  have  explained  above  still 


THE  EMERGENT  THEORY  OF  MIND  705 

prevails.  Only  it  is  important  to  remember  what  different  meanings 
the  word  "consciousness"  actually  has,  and  in  its  two  legitimate 
meanings  to  keep  it  distinguished  from  the  larger  term,  mind. 

Those  of  us  who  have  had  the  experience  of  awaking  from  the 
unconsciousness  of  ether  or  some  other  anaesthetic  have  perhaps  had 
a  good  illustration  of  the  two  kinds  of  consciousness  to  which  I  have 
referred.  There  is  first  a  mere  awareness  of  certain  noises,  perhaps 
of  the  nurses'  voices,  not  brought  into  relation  to  "myself,"  or  to 
the  total  situation.  Consciousness  thus  far  is  simply  the  relation 
between  a  percipient  subject  and  an  object.  Gradually,  however, 
the  situation  dawns.  I  am  here  and  have  been  asleep.  The  voices, 
myself,  the  environment,  my  immediate  past,  are  knit  together  into 
a  connected  story.  I  have  regained  my  consciousness.  The  per- 
ceived object  has  been  brought  into  relation,  not  only  with  the  per- 
cipient subject,  but  with  a  lot  of  other  things,  names  and  memories. 
The  perceived  thing  gets  a  meaning,  as  we  say,  that  is,  it  takes 
its  place  in  a  familiar  group  of  memory  images,  making  a  connected 
story.3  We  have  here  merely  a  more  complex  form  of  togetherness, 
but  so  far  as  the  nature  of  consciousness  itself  is  concerned  or  its 
connection  with  the  body  our  conclusions  are  not  changed.  What 
I  have  said  of  awareness  applies  also  here. 

If  now  anyone  should  not  be  satisfied  with  this  very  simple 
description  of  consciousness  and  its  relation  to  the  body  and  should 
insist  that  we  have  in  consciousness  something  more  than  such  a 
"  compresence "  as  I  have  described,  such  for  instance  as  recent 
writers  have  called  "a  new  dimension  of  reality"  or  "an  indepen- 
dent variable,"  I  can  not  see  that  it  would  make  any  difference  so 
far  as  my  conclusions  about  the  relation  of  mind  and  body  are  con- 
cerned. If,  however,  one  begins  to  speak  about  consciousness  as  a 
creative  agent,  or  an  effective  factor  in  the  world,  why,  then  one 
is  speaking  not  of  consciousness  but  of  mind.  The  emergent  theory 
would  then  hold  good. 

My  only  present  purpose  is  to  show  that  in  dealing  with  the 
mind-body  problem  consciousness  must  be  considered  as  just  one 
distinct  pjjaj^  of  that  total  complex  thing  which  we  call  the  mind 
and  dealt  with  by  itself  in  its  relation  to  the  body,  and  that  if  the 
connected  story  theory  of  consciousness  is  correct,  it  is  just  a  peculiar 
kind  of  relation  between  things  and  hence  comes  neither  under  the 
emergent  theory  nor  any  of  the  old  parallelistic,  interaction,  or 
double-aspect  theories. 

This  is  the  second  "wave."  A  third,  if  one  were  to  solve  the 
mind-body  problem,  would  have  to  be  met  and  surmounted. 

»  Comp.  the  full  theory  of  consciousness  given  by  Bertrand  Kussell  in  his 
Analysis  of  Mind,  already  referred  to,  p.  288ff. 


706  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

If  by  mind  we  mean  adaptive  behavior,  intelligent  control,  spe- 
cific response  plus  consciousness,  then  the  above-described  solution 
of  the  mind-body  problem  may  suffice.  But  mind  is  a  still  broader 
term.  It  includes  the  primary  biological  "interests,"  which  be- 
long to  the  living  organism  itself.  Now  while  there  is  a  strong  ten- 
dency in  present-day  psychology,  sociology,  education,  etc.,  to  elevate 
to  a  position  of  first  importance  the  conative  tendencies,  instinctive 
cravings,  non-reflexional  elements  of  experience,  the  wish,  the  will, 
the  libido,  the  power  of  self-maintenance  which  belongs  to  all  life, 
the  vital  principle,  elan  vital,  or  whatever  it  is,  nevertheless,  in  recent 
discussions  about  the  real  nature  of  mind  and  consciousness,  which 
have  filled  this  JOURNAL,  and  others,  these  primary  biological  im- 
pulses have  not  been  sufficiently  noticed.  Professor  Perry,  near 
the  conclusion  of  his  chapter  on  "A  Realistic  Theory  of  Mind"  in 
his  Present  Philosophical  Tendencies,  recognizing  the  complex  char- 
acter of  the  mind,  says  that  it  embraces  three  parts.  First,  a  com- 
plex acting  desideratively  or  interestedly,  characterized  by  certain 
biological  interests.  Second,  a  nervous  system  acting  as  instrument 
of  the  above  interests.  Third,  certain  contents  or  parts  of  the  en- 
vironment, called  the  mental  contents. 

It  is  not  the  place  here  to  ask  why  Professor  Perry  did  not  add 
consciousness  to  these  three  parts,  making  four,  nor  to  raise  the 
question  whether  the  analysis  would  not  have  been  more  accurate 
if  he  had  substituted  consciousness  as  the  third  and  last  element 
in  mind  in  place  of  the  problematical  "contents,"  as  I  should  be 
inclined  to  do,  thus  limiting  the  mind  to  a  series  of  interests  and 
activities  plus  consciousness.  This  question  does  not  belong  here. 
I  am  only  concerned  in  calling  attention  to  the  fact  that  the  pri- 
mary biological  interests  belong  to  that  very  complex  thing  which 
we  call  the  mind  and  in  asking  how  this  additional  factor  would 
bear  upon  the  mind-body  problem. 

It  begins  to  appear  more  than  ever  that  the  mind-body  problem 
is  a  kind  of  pseudo-problem  and  the  traditional  "solutions"  all  quite 
beside  the  mark.  The  relation  between  the  mind  and  the  body  may 
be  quite  different  depending  upon  whether  we  are  talking  about  the 
springs  of  behavior,  namely,  the  primary  biological  interests,  or 
about  adaptive  behavior  itself,  or  about  consciousness.  Evidently 
man 's  original  nature,  his  primitive  impulses,  his  primary  biological 
interests,  do  not  "emerge"  from  the  organization  of  his  vital  proc- 
esses. They  are  the  vital  processes  or  a  part  of  them.  The  fact 
is,  of  course,  that  we  are  not  in  position  to  discuss  this  problem  at 
all,  because  we  do  not  know  enough  about  vital  processes,  the  springs 
of  life,  to  determine  their  relation  to  the  body.  We  at  once  divide 
into  schools.  According  to  M.  Bergson,  not  only  does  the  vital  im- 


THE  EMERGENT  THEORY  OF  MIND  707 

pulse  not  emerge  from  the  body  but  the  exact  reverse  is  thought 
to  be  true.  Matter  is  a  kind  of  emergent  from  the  vital  impulse. 
On  the  other  hand,  according  to  the  extreme  Behaviorists  and  the 
Materialists,  life  itself  and  of  course  all  its  impulses  and  interests 
are  the  products  of  material  organization.  In  this  sense,  I  suppose, 
the  primary  impulses  could  be  said  to  emerge  from  matter,  although 
not  from  the  body ;  for  the  body,  at  any  rate  the  brain,  is  a  kind  of 
instrument  of  these  primary  impulses,  a  means  of  controlling  the 
environment  to  their  ends.  If  so,  then  it  would  seem  that  the  pri- 
mary biological  interests  emerge  from  matter,  and  the  brain  (and 
hence  the  mind)  emerges  from  the  primary  biological  interests.  At 
any  rate  the  emergent  theory  seems  to  fit  in  here  also  better  than 
any  of  the  old  parallelistic,  interaction,  or  double-aspect  theories. 

Mr.  Louis  Berman,  in  his  book  The  Glands  Regulating  Personality, 
speaks  of  the  lowest  organs,  the  vegetative  organs,  the  heart  and 
lungs,  stomach  and  intestines,  the  kidneys  and  the  liver,  and  the 
glands  of  internal  secretion  as  inventing  and  elaborating  muscle, 
bone,  and  brain  to  carry  out  their  will.  Evolution,  he  says,  has  been 
in  the  direction  of  a  greater  perfection  of  methods  of  carrying  out 
their  will.  "Mind,  reacting  upon  its  creator,  has,  in  a  sense,  come 
to  dominate  them,  because  it  has  become  the  meeting  ground  of  all 
the  energy-influences  seething  and  bubbling  in  the  organism,  and  so 
developed  into  the  organ  of  handling  them  as  a  whole,  their  Inte- 
grating-Executive. ' '  * 

Here  we  seem  to  have  an  answer  to  the  question  which  American 
Instrumentalism  never  made  clear.  Instrumentalism  tells  us  what 
the  mind  is  the  intrument  for,  but  not  very  confidently  what  it  is 
the  instrument  of.  According  to  Professor  Berman,  it  is  the  instru- 
ment of  the  vegetative  organs,  heart,  lungs,  etc.,  for  carrying  out 
their  will,  or  the  instrument  of  the  "energy-influences  seething  and 
bubbling  in  the  organism. ' ' 5 

*  Page  196. 

5  To  my  mind  Professor  Berman  spoils  this  excellent  description  by  pre- 
facing it  with  his  theory  that  consciousness  or  awareness  must  be  accepted  as  a 
fundamental,  primal  fact,  like  protoplasm.  "Consciousness  and  protoplasm  may 
be  the  complementary  sides  of  the  same  coin. "  In  a  somewhat  similar  way,  Dr. 
Alexander,  in  his  Space,  Time,  and  Deity,  seems  to  me  to  relapse  into  a  kind  of 
double-aspect  theory  after  having  given  the  clearest  possible  account  of  the 
emergent  theory.  He  reiterates  throughout  his  book  his  excellent  theory  that 
the  mind  emerges  from  a  lower  level  of  complexity  which  we  call  vital,  but  still 
finds  it  necessary  to  teach  that  "the  mental  process  and  the  neural  process  are 
one  and  the  same  existence,  not  two  existences.  As  mental,  it  is  in  my  language 
enjoyed  by  the  experient;  as  neural  it  is  contemplated  by  an  outsider  or  may 
b«  contemplated  in  thought  by  the  experient  himself."  (Vol.  II,  p.  9.)  Simi- 
larly Professor  Montague,  after  identifying  consciousness  with  potential  energy, 
existing  in  space,  says  that  "what  we  know  directly  from  within  as  the 


708  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Returning,  however,  to  our  main  inquiry,  we  are  not  told  by 
Professor  Berman  how  the  energy-influences  are  related  to  the  body. 
In  other  words,  nobody  knows  anything  about  the  "energy-influ- 
ences," "conative  tendencies,"  "biological  interests,"  "self-main- 
tenance of  system  C,"  "elan  vital,"  or  whatever  we  choose  to  call  it 
or  them,  so  it  is  useless  to  discuss  this  part  of  the  mind-body  problem. 
Although  I  should  prefer  the  vitalistic  method  of  approach  here, 
probably  most  of  the  readers  of  this  JOURNAL  would  rather  think  of 
the  primary  biological  interests  as  the  result  of  the  organization 
of  simpler  material  elements.  In  the  latter  case  the  emergent  theory 
fits  in  better  than  any  of  the  older  views.  Incidentally  I  may  call 
attention  to  the  fact  that,  if  one  assumes  that  the  biological  interests 
emerge  from  the  organization  of  material  atoms,  this  apparently 
behavioristic  or  materialistic  solution  of  the  question  does  not  lead 
in  the  direction  of  an  ontological  materialistic  monism  or  any  kind 
of  monism,  first,  because,  since  so  much  is  made  of  the  result  of 
organization  and  integration,  the  organizing  or  integrating  agency 
is  still  to  be  accounted  for;  second,  because  no  one  knows  what  the 
first  elements  are  with  which  the  organization  begins,  electrons  being 
simply  our  present  stopping  place;  and  third,  because  the  whole 
view  is  pluralistic.  What  we  have  is  a  hierarchy  of  entities  increas- 
ing in  "value"  with  each  new  integration  of  the  next  lower  proc- 
eases.  But  in  these  philosophical  problems  I  am  not  for  the  moment 
interested. 

Summarizing,  I  believe  it  is  helpful  to  keep  in  view  that  the 
word  "mind"  (in  its  wider  meaning)  includes  three  things:  first, 
the  primary  biological  interests:  second,  adaptive  behavior  (mind 
in  its  narrower  meaning)  :  third,  consciousness.  The  classical  solu- 
tions of  the  mind-body  problem,  parallelism,  interactionism,  double- 
aspect  theory,  epiphenomenalism,  etc.,  do  not  apply  to  any  of  these, 
although  we  know  little  about  the  first.  The  emergent  theory  seems 
better  all  around. 

G.  T.  W.  PAIBICK. 
UNIVERSITY  or  IOWA. 


TWO  NOTES  ON  ESTHETICS 

rriHE  discussion  of  esthetics  in  Vol.  XIX,  No.  5  of  this  JOURNAL 

raised  two  points  which  seem  to  invite  further  consideration. 

One  is  Mr.  Pepper's  "common-sense  concept"  for  a  working  unit 

psychical  or  subjective  side  of  experience  may  be  the  same  as  what  we  know 
indirectly  from  without  as  the  potential  energy  of  the  nerve  currents  in  the 
brain."  (Monist,  Vol.  XVIII,  p.  27.)  I  am  myself  unable  to  see  why  either  the 
emergent  theory  of  Dr.  Alexander  or  the  energy  theory  of  Professor  Montague 
needs  to  be  supplemented  by  introducing  any  double-aspect  view. 


TWO  NOTES  ON  ESTHETICS  709 

in  esthetics ;  the  other  is  the  relation  of  beauty  to  utility,  in  part  as 
related  to  that  concept. 

I 

Mr.  Pepper 's  concept  is  first  defined  as  ' '  the  liking  of  a  thing  for 
itself  in  contrast  to  the  valuing  of  a  thing  as  a  means  to  something 
else, ' '  and  a  little  further  on  as  ' '  things  valued  for  themselves  inde- 
pendent of  all  practical  considerations."  I  am  not  sure  that  these 
two  statements  are  wholly  consistent ;  but  that  we  can  better  decide 
later.  The  first  element,  the  "liking  of  a  thing  for  itself,"  corre- 
sponds pretty  closely  to  the  criterion  of  beauty  in  St.  Thomas 
Aquinas :  Id  cujus  ipsa  apprehensio  placet,  already  brought  forward 
as  a  working  conception  in  Mr.  Carritt's  Theory  of  Beauty,  p.  9.  It 
may  be  helpful  to  examine  this  phrase  in  its  context,  and  in  the 
light  of  some  other  passages  in  Aquinas,  with  a  view  to  seeing  their 
implications. 

The  phrase  occurs  in  a  discussion  of  the  statement  that  "not  only 
the  good  but  also  the  beautiful  is  loved  by  every  one,"  which  runs 
as  follows:  "The  beautiful  is  the  same  as  the  good,  differing  only 
in  the  way  we  conceive  it  (ratione).  Since  the  good  is  that  which 
all  desire,  it  is  of  the  nature  of  the  good  that  in  it  desire  finds  rest. 
But  it  pertains  to  the  nature  of  the  beautiful  that  at  the  sight  or 
knowledge  of  it  perception  (apprehensio)  finds  rest.  Hence  those 
senses  especially  consider  beauty  which  are  in  closest  touch  with 
knowledge  (maxime  cognoscitivi) ,  that  is,  sight  and  hearing,  which 
serve  the  reason;  for  we  speak  of  beautiful  sights  and  beautiful 
sounds.  But  in  reference  to  the  objects  of  the  other  senses  we  do 
not  use  the  name  of  beauty ;  for  we  do  not  speak  of  beautiful  tastes 
or  smells.  Hence  it  is  clear  that  the  beautiful  adds  to  the  good  a 
certain  order  with  reference  to  the  power  of  knowledge ;  so  that  we 
may  call  'good'  that  which  simply  satisfies  desire,  and  'beautiful' 
that  of  which  the  very  perception  is  pleasing"  (Summa,  la,  2ae, 
q.  27,  art.  1 ;  II,  p.  224 1).  In  another  place  the  requisites  of  beauty 
are  stated  to  be  three:  "First,  wholeness  or  perfection;  for  things 
which  are  diminished  are  by  that  very  fact  ugly;  second,  due  pro- 
portion, or  consonance ;  and  lastly,  clarity ;  for  which  reason  things 
which  have  a  bright  color  are  said  to  be  beautiful"  (Summa,  la,  2ae, 
q.  39,  art.  8).  But  the  idea  of  proportion,  as  Aquinas  was  well 
aware,  introduces  an  element  of  relation :  "It  must  be  said  that 
beauty,  health,  and  the  like  are  spoken  of  with  reference  to  some- 
thing; for  a  certain  tempering  of  the  humors  makes  health  in  a 
youth  as  it  does  not  in  an  old  man ;  and  there  is  a  certain  health  in 
a  lion  which  is  death  to  a  man.  Hence  health  is  a  proportion  of  the 
i  References  to  volume  and  page  are  to  the  edition  of  Frette  and  Mare. 


710  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

humors  with  reference  to  a  certain  nature.  And  so  beauty  consists 
in  a  proportion  of  members  and  colors"  (Comm.  on  Psalm  XLIV; 
XVIII,  p.  504).  Here  Aquinas  (like  Bacon  in  his  essay  on  beauty) 
is  thinking  mainly  of  personal  human  beauty;  yet  the  remarks  of 
both  have  an  obvious  extension  to  other  ranges. 

Thus  we  find  in  the  context  of  our  formula  a  good  many  qualifi- 
cations. Beauty  may  involve  an  element  of  knowledge,  as  well  as 
of  purely  emotional  reaction ;  it  may  be  apprehended  under  changing 
conditions,  and  these  changes  may  alter  our  apprehension  of  it. 
In  view  of  these  considerations,  can  the  formula  carry  us  very  far 
without  being  interpreted,  and  can  it  be  interpreted  without  differ- 
ences of  opinion?  Is  the  reliable  perception  of  beauty  that  which 
we  gain  at  first  sight,  or  that  which  we  arrive  at  only  gradually! 
Or  is  the  pleasure  to  be  only  that  which  we  feel  at  the  first  moment  ? 
I  take  it  that  cases  in  which  the  beauty  of  something  is  by  no  means, 
or  only  very  imperfectly,  perceived  at  first  sight  are  familiar  enough 
to  us  all.  And  again,  is  every  one 's  first  perception  of  and  pleasure 
in  beauty  of  equal  value?  If  so,  we  must  probably  reduce  esthetic 
perceptions  to  the  very  simplest  cases ;  if  not,  the  door  to  divergence 
of  opinion  swings  wide  open  again.  "If  these  men  would  let  the 
trimmings  go,"  says  Mr.  Pepper,  "they  could  cooperate  and  work 
in  harmony."  They  could,  perhaps,  but  would  they?  And  they 
might  not  even  agree  with  Mr.  Pepper  as  to  the  real  nature  of  "trim- 
mings." 

Meanwhile,  it  may  be  profitable  to  push  our  inquiry  into  Aquinas 
a  little  farther.  It  is  clear  that  he  recognizes  a  connection  between 
the  beautiful  and  the  good,  and  the  presence  of  an  intellectual 
element  in  the  former.  Here  is  another  passage  bearing  on  the 
first  point:  "The  beautiful  and  the  good  are  indeed  the  same  thing 
at  bottom  (in  subjecto),  because  they  are  founded  on  the  same 
thing,  to  wit,  form,  and  on  this  account  the  good  is  praised  as  beau- 
tiful; but  they  differ  in  the  way  we  think  of  them  (ratione).  The 
good  properly  has  reference  to  desire ;  for  the  good  is  that  which  all 
things  desire,  and  so  it  has  the  nature  of  an  end;  for  desire  is  a 
certain  motion  toward  a  thing.  But  the  beautiful  has  reference  to 
the  power  of  cognition,  for  those  things  are  called  beautiful  which 
when  seen  are  pleasing.  Hence  the  beautiful  consists  in  due  propor- 
tion, because  the  senses  are  pleased  by  things  that  are  duly  propor- 
tioned, as  by  those  that  are  like  themselves;  for  sense  is  a  certain 
ratio,  and  so  is  every  power  of  cognition.  And  since  cognition  is 
effected  by  assimilation,  and  likeness  has  reference  to  form,  the 
beautiful  properly  pertains  to  the  naturte  of  a  formal  cause" 
(Summa,  la,  lae,  q.  5,  art.  4;  I,  p.  38).  Not  only  so,  but  the  de- 


711 

sires  for  the  beautiful  and  for  the  good  are  not  really  separate: 
"It  must  be  said  that  the  ending  of  desire  in  the  good  and  the 
beautiful  and  peace  is  not  an  ending  in  different  things.  For  by 
the  very  fact  that  anything  desires  the  good,  it  desires  at  the  same 
time  the  beautiful  and  peace ;  the  beautiful,  in  so  far  as  it  is  in  itself 
modified  and  specified,2  which  is  included  in  the  nature  of  the 
good;  but  the  good  adds  an  order  of  perfecting  to  other  things. 
Peace,  again,  imports  the  removal  of  perturbations  and  the  gain- 
ing of  what  is  sought.  But  the  very  fact  of  desiring  means  the 
desire  to  remove  what  stands  in  the  way  of  it.  Hence  by  the  same 
desire  we  desire  the  good,  the  beautiful,  and  peace"  (De  Veritate, 
q.  22,  art.  1;  XV,  p.  144). 

So  much,  then,  for  the  connection  and  the  difference  between 
goodness  and  beauty,  as  Aquinas  conceived  them ;  and  if  we  discount 
the  scholastic  terminology,  we  shall  find  in  his  account  (which  is,  of 
course,  entirely  incidental  to  his  larger  purpose)  a  good  deal  with 
which  we  may  agree.  For  myself,  I  do  not  feel  that  beauty  can 
be  restricted  to  the  emotional,  but  rather  that  an  intellectual  element 
is,  or  may  be,  present  in  it.  The  requisite  of  "wholeness  or  per- 
fection" has  perhaps  some  relation  to  Croce's  contention  that  there 
are  degrees  of  ugliness  but  not  of  beauty,  and  shows  how  that  con- 
tention should  be  interpreted.  The  idea  of  beauty  as  in  part  arising 
from  the  relation  to  an  observer  or  recipient  is  one  which  a  sound 
esthetic  can  hardly  leave  out  of  account.  Finally,  in  the  correlation 
of  beauty,  goodness,  and  peace  there  is  a  reference  to  that  feature 
of  the  esthetic  experience  which  a  too  little  known  poet  has  called 
"the  strange  quietude  of  human  art."  These  are  points  noted  in 
passing;  I  am  not  trying  to  coordinate  them,  much  less  to  work 
them  into  a  systematic  presentation. 

What  now  are  we  to  understand  by  Mr.  Pepper's  values  "in- 
dependent of  all  practical  considerations"?  Do  they  mean  instru- 
mental values  in  general,  or  are  they  to  be  more  narrowly  inter- 
preted, in  the  sense  of  the  strictly  utilitarian?  If  the  former,  it 
can  hardly  be  maintained  that  instrumental  values  can  have  no 
place  in  the  esthetic  experience ;  if  the  latter,  we  are  led  directly  to 
the  second  point  which  I  wish  to  discuss. 

II 

The  good  old  notion  that  utility  is  a  self-evident  concept,  the 
applications  of  which  are  immediately  clear,  was  a  great  labor- 
saver.  Apply  it  to  a  given  experience,  note  the  elements  it  ex- 

2  ' '  For  the  beautiful  adds,  over  and  above  a  good  order  with  reference  to 
the  power  of  knowing,  that  the  fact  should  be  of  a  certain  kind"  (Comm.  on 
Dionysius,  c.  IV,  lect.  5;  xxix,  p.  443). 


712  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

plains,  and  set  down  the  remainder  to  such  minor  considerations 
as  the  esthetic.  Nothing  could  in  appearance  be  simpler,  even  if 
the  result  might  be  such  cheerful  flippancy  as  William  James's  coup- 
ling of  psychiatry  as  the  study  of  the  harmful  in  mental  life 
with  esthetics  as  the  study  of  the  useless.  Unfortunately,  the  notion 
of  utility  is  both  complex  and  highly  relative;  and  we  can  not 
see  either  its  various  degrees  or  its  applications  to  art  without 
careful  scrutiny. 

In  ordinary  life,  the  criterion  of  utility  is  specific  application; 
a  thing  is  seen  to  be  useful  just  in  so  far  as  it  immediately  meets 
a  specific  need.  But  the  more  specialized  it  becomes,  the  less  adapted 
it  is  to  any  but  its  own  special  situation.  A  saw  is  useful  only  for 
a  particular  operation,  and  a  keyhole  saw  only  for  a  particular 
kind  of  sawing;  and  either  is  of  "use"  only  when  both  desire  and 
opportunity  for  sawing  are  present.  But  we  should  think  it  pal- 
pably absurd  to  call  a  good  tool  "useless"  when  it  is  merely  un- 
employed, that  is,  in  the  absence  of  the  situation  to  which  it  is 
adapted.  Now  the  case  is  not  radically  altered  when  we  turn  to 
spiritual  processes  and  capacities.  It  is  true  that  the  latter  are 
not,  and  can  not  be,  so  directly  fitted  to  immediate  situations  as  are 
material  tools;  and  there  is,  further,  a  greater  need  of  specific  re- 
sponse by  the  other  factor  in  the  situation.  But  the  element  of 
response  is  not  wholly  lacking  even  in  the  case  of  tools ;  it  requires 
a  certain  type  of  saw  to  cut  metal,  or  to  cut  wood  to  the  best  ad- 
vantage, and  a  screwdriver  is  not  very  effective  on  an  uncut  screw- 
head.  Thus  it  does  not  seem  that  there  is  a  radical  difference  be- 
tween the  two  groups  of  cases,  but  rather  a  difference  of  emphasis 
in  common  elements. 

Looking  now  more  carefully  at  the  applications  of  utility,  we 
can  for  convenience  distinguish  four  major  forms.  First,  there  is 
that  which  has  immediate  special  application,  like  a  title-deed,  which 
refers  to  a  specific  actual  "here  and  now,"  and  has  no  explicit  refer- 
ence to  anything  else.  Secondly,  there  is  that  which  has  mediate 
special  application,  like  a  statute,  which  prescribes  how  a  specific 
situation  is  to  be  dealt  with  if  it  occurs,  but  does  not  specify  when 
or  where  it  will  occur,  or  even  that  it  will  necessarily  occur  at  all. 
Thirdly,  there  is  that  which  has  immediate  general  application,  like 
the  multiplication  table,  adaptable  to  an  indefinite  number  of  situa- 
tions, which  must  occur  in  some  experience ;  but  the  kind  and  manner 
of  the  experience  are  not  specified,  beyond  the  presupposition  of 
ability  to  figure  correctly.  And  fourthly,  there  is  that  which  has 
mediate  general  application,  depending  on  adaptation  to  a  specific 
response,  which  must  be  furnished  in  and  by  an  individual  experi- 


TWO  NOTES  ON  ESTHETICS  713 

ence.  To  this  class  belong,  among  others,  religious  rituals  and  works 
of  art.  To  say  that  the  response  to  the  appeal  of  a  work  of  art  is 
"useless"  because  it  does  not  lead  to  a  concrete  action  seems  to  me 
misleading.  Sometimes  it  does  issue  in  action;  often  it  may  lead 
to  a  beneficial  heightening  of  the  perception  of  the  meaning  of 
experience.  Nor  is  concrete  action  always,  in  the  broader  sense, 
"useful."  The  tendency  of  an  individual  to  self-preservation  need 
not  be  wholly  useful  even  to  him,  and  certainly  need  not  be  so 
to  others;  and  the  need  of  self-expression  in  an  art  may  be  so  im- 
perative that  the  satisfaction  of  it  will  be  as  useful  to  its  possessor, 
in  the  sense  of  maintaining  the  equilibrium  of  his  personality,  as 
the  satisfaction  of  any  other  personal  need. 

Obviously,  as  we  go  through  the  sequence  of  utilities  thus  roughly 
distinguished,  the  place  of  "utility"  in  the  narrow  sense  of  immedi- 
ate and  specific  application  grows  smaller,  and  the  place  of  other 
values,  including  the  esthetic,  grows  larger.  It  is  now  important 
to  notice  that  below  the  level  of  the  simple  utility  is  another  level, 
that  of  the  extemporized  solution — the  makeshift.  This  we  may 
tolerate,  as  the  best  way  out  of  gravely  hampering  conditions;  but 
we  do  not  admire  it  for  itself,  and  as  a  constant  reliance  it  betrays 
its  user.  The  habitual  use  of  makeshifts  turns  into  shiftlessness. 
Just  so,  an  action  which,  even  skilfully,  evades  a  real  moral  issue 
leaves  us  guarded  or  squeamish  in  our  admiration,  and  certainly 
causes  us  no  glow  of  satisfaction. 

Let  us  say,  then,  that  immediately  recognized  specific  utility  is 
the  zero  point  on  a  scale  of  values.  Below  it  is  the  region  of  make- 
shifts and  patchwork;  just  above  it  is  the  region  of  devices  which 
with  some  measure  of  skill  meet  a  real  need,  or  even  any  presented 
situation.  Now,  just  as  below  the  zero  point  any  satisfaction  which 
we  feel  is  either  misplaced  or  apologetic,  so  at  the  zero  point  we 
feel  no  distinguishable  satisfaction,  because  both  situation  and  solu- 
tion pass  immediately  and  without  analysis  into  the  general  current 
of  experience.  But  as  we  go  up  the  scale,  satisfaction  rises  into 
consciousness  as  a  distinct  element,  and  tends  to  be  deepened  and 
diversified.  In  watching  any  sort  of  "good  job"  we  feel  a  pleasure 
which  is  not  explained  by  any  practical  relation  in  which  we  stand 
to  it — but  which  is  not  always  impaired  by  such  a  relation,  for  we 
may  feel  the  same  sort  of  pleasure  in  connection  with  an  activity 
of  our  own.  What  first  makes  this  reaction  possible  is  the  fact  that 
we  can  find  leisure  to  stand  off  a  little  from  the  experience,  and  so 
appraise  in  it  other  values  than  the  purely  practical.  Then,  the 
higher  in  the  scale  we  go,  the  wider  is  the  circle  of  possible  adapta- 
tions, the  less  crudely  material  the  aim,  so  that  the  attitude  of 


714  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

purely  esthetic  contemplation  grows  correspondingly  easier.  But 
if  we  cut  loose  entirely  from  the  original  basis  of  the  experience, 
or  if  we  try  to  assume  an  attitude  of  detachment  without  anything 
from  which  to  be  detached,  the  desired  esthetic  reaction  will  be 
either  falsified  or  demolished. 

This  conception  of  a  scale  of  values  in  which  utility  and  beauty 
are  gradually  distinguished,  and  the  latter  made  more  prominent 
than  the  former,  enables  us  to  see  just  where  the  fallacy  of  "inde- 
pendence of  practical  considerations"  takes  its  rise.  It  is  easy  to 
argue  that  because  the  element  grows  less  and  less  marked,  a  point 
may  be  reached  at  which  it  will  vanish  entirely,  and  a  "pure" 
esthetic  value  remain;  and  such  a  view  has  often  been  held.  I 
quote,  for  instance,  the  words  of  a  writer  noted  for  cautiousness  of 
statement,  who  also  has  a  sound  view  of  the  general  nature  of  the 
esthetic  experience:  "All  Fine  Art,  then,  we  may  say,  is  founded 
originally  in  satisfied  utility,  and  in  some  cases  continues  dependent 
on  it  to  the  last.  It  is  conditioned  by  the  utility  out  of  which  it 
arises,  and  with  which  it  is  contrasted.  And  thus,  when  we  look 
at  the  Fine  Arts  in  their  full  development,  a  distinction  is  plainly 
to  be  drawn  between  those  which  continue  throughout  to  be  con- 
ditioned upon  the  prior  satisfaction  of  some  specific  non-artistic 
utility,  and  those  which  are  cut  loose  from  such  specific  dependence, 
and  have  a  free  self -centered  existence  of  their  own. ' ' 3  The  doctrine 
of  the  first  two  sentences  is  absolutely  sound ;  but  that  of  the  third 
introduces  the  fallacy.  The  practical  consideration  may  be  indefi- 
nitely attenuated,  but  it  is  never  wholly  lost ;  we  no  more  encounter 
disembodied  arts  than  we  encounter  disembodied  human  beings  in 
ordinary  life.  Even  in  an  observer  the  question  of  esthetic  response 
can  not  be  wholly  divorced  from  considerations  which  may  broadly 
be  termed  "practical";  still  less  so  can  it  be  if  we  consider  the  ac- 
tivity of  the  artist.  The  qualities  of  pigments  or  the  nature  of 
a  plastered  wall  are  of  practical  concern  to  the  painter,  the  ranges 
and  timbres  of  musical  instruments  to  a  composer,  the  associations 
of  words  to  a  poet,  and  so  on  indefinitely;  and  these  form  but  a 
single  range  of  such  considerations.  I  doubt  if  a  serious  artist 
often  sets  to  work  in  entire  disregard  of  them;  and  it  is  certainly 
the  case  that  artists  who  profess  a  lordly  disdain  of  them  generally 
come  to  grief. 

I  conclude,  then,  that  Mr.  Pepper 's  concept  is  at  best  a  sign-post, 
which  can  only  direct  us  toward  a  theory  of  valuation  to  be  worked 
out  on  its  own  merits,  with  as  much  conflict  of  opinions  as  may  be 
necessary.  We  may  grant  that  "things  valued  for  themselves" 

*8hadworth  Hodgson,  The  Metaphysic  of  Experience,  III,  p.  435. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  715 

exist,  though  I  think  we  can  do  so  only  after  careful  definition ;  but 
even  if  we  do,  we  may  still  hold  that  such  values  need  not  be  self- 
evident,  and  ask  under  what  conditions  they  are  to  be  recognized. 
As  for  "independence  of  all  practical  considerations,"  that  is  a 
phrase  too  vague  to  be  helpful  unless  interpreted ;  and  if  it  be  inter- 
preted as  making  the  esthetic  attitude  the  polar  antithesis  of  the 
practical,  it  seems  to  be  setting  up  an  unnecessary  and  untenable 
dualism.  For  my  part,  I  believe  that  a  better  point  of  departure 
would  be  the  conception  of  beauty  not  as  something  aimed  at  ~by  an 
experience,  but  as  something  which  comes  to  be  recognized  in  an 
experience.  If  this  is  what  Aquinas  meant  by  calling  it  a  formal, 
not  a  final,  cause,  he  was  profoundly  right. 

CHARLES  E.  WHITMORE. 
NORTHAMPTON,  MASSACHUSETTS. 


BOOK  EEVIEWS 

Foundations  of  Formal  Logic.     H.  BRADFORD  SMITH.     University 

of  Pennsylvania  Press,  1922.    56  pp. 

In  this  pamphlet,  which  is  intended  for  use  in  the  classroom, 
Mr.  Smith  treats  some  of  the  problems  of  logic  from  a  very  special 
angle,  so  that  we  can  not  leave  the  work  without  the  question — 
are  these  the  foundations  of  logic?  Modern  mathematical  logic  has 
so  broadened  the  Aristotelian  and  Medieeval  conceptions  of  the  sub- 
ject that  we  anticipate  much  more  than  a  treatment  of  the  syllogism 
in  a  paper  which  has  the  mathematical  form;  and  yet  Mr.  Smith 
restricts  himself  to  the  syllogism,  its  moods  and  figures,  with  a  few 
paragraphs  on  immediate  inference.  The  exposition  makes  use  of 
a  quasi-mathematical  symbolism  which  involves  many  of  the  ideas 
of  more  familiar  logical  calculuses,  but  the  total  impression  is 
one  of  clumsiness  and  inelegance.  Though  the  avowed  purpose  of 
such  a  symbolism  is  to  add  clarity,  Mr.  Smith's  symbols  confuse 
rather  than  illuminate:  his  system  lacks  the  simplicity  and  com- 
pleteness which  we  have  been  led  to  expect  from  mathematical  logic. 

We  are  able,  however,  to  extract  the  following  points  from  the 
paper:  (1)  Mr.  Smith  believes  that  the  subject-matter  of  logic 
is  a  certain  number  of  propositions  about  classes.  "The  problem 
of  a  deductive  science,"  he  tells  us,  "is  to  define  its  elements  .  .  . 
by  an  enumeration  of  their  formal  properties.  The  task  of  logic  is, 
then,  to  develop  its  own  system  by  constructing  all  the  true  and 
all  the  untrue  propositions  into  which  its  elements  enter  exclusively." 
These  elements  are,  for  Mr.  Smith,  classes.  This  is  a  debatable  point 
since  we  have  learned  from  Peano  and  Russell,  from  Couturat  and 


716  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

others,  that  logic  need  not  confine  itself  to  classes  and  class  relation- 
ships, that  among  its  elements  are  to  be  found  prepositional  func- 
tions, propositions,  concepts,  relations,  operations — entities  in  terms 
of  which  classes  can  be  defined  but  which  are  not  classes.  This  is 
one  reason  why  Mr.  Smith's  book  is  misnamed:  a  study  of  the 
fundamentals  of  logic  should  include  more  than  propositions  (or 
propositional  functions)  about  classes.  A  class  calculus  of  any 
sort  is  not  the  whole  of  logic;  it  is  merely  one  aspect  of  a  subject 
which  refuses  to  be  confined  within  the  narrow  walls  of  definitions. 

(2)  The  class  calculus  which  Mr.  Smith  constructs — by  the  aid 
of  Euler's  circular  diagrams — differs  from  other  class  calculuses  in 
that  its  aim  is  to  represent  the  varieties  of  the  Aristotelian  syllogism. 
He  selects  four  basic  types  of  proposition   (about  classes),  which 
are  roughly  equivalent  to  the  A,  I,  and  E  of  traditional  logic  and 
which   embody  all  of  the  possible  relations  between  two  classes. 
The  syllogism  is  then  described  as  a  form  of  implication  which  deter- 
mines the  relation  between  classes  c  and  a  when  any  of  these  rela- 
tions holds  between  a  and  b,  and  between  &  and  c  respectively.     (By 
the  untruths  of  logic,  Mr.  Smith  means  all  of  the  possible  ways  of 
going  astray  in  the  syllogism,  i.e.,  all  of  the  possible  formal  fallacies.) 
It  is  not  surprising  that  this  class  calculus,  despite  its  symbolic  form, 
conveys  no  new  information  about  the  syllogism :   there  is  probably 
no  new  information  to  be  had ;  and  the  theory  of  the  mediaeval  logi- 
cians, apart  from  the  form  of  its  expression,  is  as  acceptable  today 
as  it  was  in  the  twelfth  century.     Logic  has  opened  new  avenues 
of  speculation  only  by  escaping  the  syllogism  and  by  giving  to  it 
a  subordinate,  though  necessary  place,  in  wider  systems. 

(3)  The  discovery  that  there  is  a  non- Aristotelian  logic  comes  as 
a  paradox  in  the  seventh  and  eighth  chapters  of  Mr.  Smith's  book. 
The  author's  postulates  for  the  syllogism  are  susceptible  of  two  in- 
terpretations in  terms  of  classes;  one  of  these  involves  the  null  and 
universal  classes  while  the  other  does  not  involve  these  classes.    We 
are  told  that  the  former,  though  further  from  ordinary  intuition, 
is  the  more  sufficient,  and  this  is  the  non-Aristotelian  logic.     It  is 
non-Aristotelian  not  because  it  deserts  the  syllogism,  but  because  it 
interprets  the  A,  E,  I,  and  0  propositions  of  Aristotle  in  a  non- 
Aristotelian  way — i.e.,  through  the  null  and  universal  classes.    This 
suggests  to  us  a  still  better  reason  for  speaking  of  Mr.  Smith's  sys- 
tem as  non-Aristotelian;  a  reason  which  would  apply  equally  well 
to  the  interpretation  which,  by  inference,  he  asserts  to  be  Aristote- 
lian.   Aristotle  did  not  believe  that  lopric  deals  with  classes  but  with 
subjects  and  predicates,  the  subjects  being  individuals,  or  first  sub- 
stances, and  the  predicates  universals.    Aristotelian  logic  is  a  sub- 


BOOK  REVIEWS  717 

J 
ject-predicate  logic,  and  subjects  and  predicates  need  not  be  classes. 

This  is  the  burden  of  such  writers  as  Mr.  Bosanquet,  who  show  that 
Aristotle  is  concerned  with  universals  or  concepts — with  genera, 
species,  definitions,  propria — and  not  with  classes. 

It  is  apparent  from  what  has  been  said  that  the  Foundations 
of  Formal  Logic  takes  us  only  a  short  distance  into  the  subject  and 
over  controversial  ground.  Its  chief  merit  will  be  to  give  to  the 
student  a  thorough  understanding  of  the  syllogism  in  a  form  which 
is  superficially  different  from  that  of  the  usual  text-book.  However, 
the  value  of  such  quasi-mathematical  expositions  of  the  syllogism, 
if  they  do  not  embody  new  ideas,  is  questionable,  and  a  teacher  of 
conservative  temper  might  prefer  the  less  complex  and  more  lucid 
methods  of  the  older  logic. 

EALPH  M.  EATON. 

HAKVAKD  COLLEGE. 

The  ^Esthetic  Attitude.  HERBERT  SIDNEY  LANGFELD.  New  York: 
Harcourt,  Brace  and  Howe.  1920.  Pp.  xi  +  287. 
In  his  preface,  Professor  Langfeld  says  modestly  that  his  book 
is  a  "description  only  of  those  problems  which  I  consider  funda- 
mental and  which  I  hope  will  serve  as  an  introduction  to  more  ex- 
tensive study."  A  reading  of  the  table  of  contents  appears  to 
bear  out  this  promise  of  a  somewhat  one-sided  treatment  of  the 
subject.  Professor  Langfeld  is  primarily  the  psychologist,  con- 
cerned largely  with  problems  of  the  esthetic  experience.  Further- 
more, it  is  as  the  instructor  of  the  entirely  uninitiated  that  he 
writes.  His  book  is  frankly  elementary,  painstakingly  supplying 
definitions  and  elucidations  of  the  simplest  matters.  For  the  most 
part  it  is  clear  and  instructive  though  remarks  on  page  16  might 
well  cause  bewilderment  even  in  those  inured  to  the  difficulties  of 
the  subject.  On  that  page  Professor  Langfeld  says  that  "Psychol- 
ogy must  analyze  the  behavior  of  the  observer  in  so  far  as  the 
peculiar  adjustment  called  'aesthetics'  is  concerned" — which  may 
of  course  be  a  misprint,  but  even  at  that  would  leave  some  things 
to  be  explained. 

As  an  introduction  to  the  definition  of  the  "science"  of  esthetics 
and  of  the  esthetic  attitude,  Professor  Langfeld  quotes  from  con- 
temporary writings  on  the  subject.  He  then  briefly  discusses  the 
various  arts  to  show  what  factors  in  them  favor  that  attitude.  Two 
chapters  he  devotes  to  the  subject  of  empathy,  and  by  citations 
from  Karl  Groos,  Lipps,  and  Vernon  Lee  renders  intelligible  this 
"motor  theory"  of  esthetic  experience.  Two  chapters  also  he  gives 
to  "Unity,"  discussing  first  the  psychological  process  by  which 
unity  is  won  out  of  diversity,  and  next  its  place  in  the  various  arts. 


718  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Again  in  two  chapters  he  devotes  himself  to  symmetry  and  balance, 
and  finally  he  has  a  chapter  on  the  Art  Impulse  in  which  he  dis- 
cnases  some  theories  as  to  its  origin. 

An  unusual  feature  of  the  volume  is  its  plates.  Many  books  of 
esthetic  theory  would  be  improved  if  they  followed  the  example 
here  set  of  including  illustrations  for  direct  elucidation  of  the  text. 
For  a  just  evaluation  of  the  work  as  a  whole  one  must  keep  strictly 
in  mind  its  avowed  scope  and  intention.  It  does  not  pretend  to  be 
either  a  complete  history  of  theory,  or  an  original  piece  of  psychol- 
ogy. It  serves  its  purpose. 

HELEN  Huss  PARKHUEST. 

BARNARD  COLLEGE. 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW.  Vol.  29,  No.  6.  Behavior  versus  In- 
trospective Psychology :  8.  W.  Fernberger.  The  Unique  in  Human 
Behavior:  H.  N.  Wieman.  Analyzed  versus  Unanalyzed  Experi- 
ence: R.  H.  Wheeler.  What  can  Psychology  Contribute  to  our 
Knowledge  of  the  Mechanism  of  Mental  Disorder?:  C.  M.  Campell. 
The  Effect  of  Variations  of  the  Intensity  of  the  Illumination  of  the 
Perimeter  Arm  on  the  Determination  of  the  Color  Fields:  C.  E. 
Ferree  and  O.  Rand.  Types  of  Dextrality:  J.  M.  Rife.  The  Sig- 
nificance of  Neural  Adjustment :  H.  C.  Warren.  The  Affiliations 
of  Behaviorism :  M .  W.  Calkins. 

STUDI  FILOSOFICI  E  RELIGIOSI.  Vol.  Ill,  Num.  3.  H  significato 
di  ypostasis  in  ad  Hebr.  I3. :  G.  Furlani.  L  'etica  di  Metodio 
d'Olimpo:  A.  Biamonti.  S.  Paolo  negli  Apologisti  greci  del  III 
secolo,  III :  M .  Fermi.  Taziano  e  lo  Gnosticismo :  M.  Zappald. 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  BULLETIN.  Vol.  19,  No.  10.  Perception:  An 
Introduction  to  the  Gestalt-Theorie :  K.  Koffka.  No.  11.  Abstracts 
of  Periodical  Literature. 

JOURNAL  OP  EXPERIMENTAL  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  V,  No.  6.  Per- 
sonality Studies  of  Three-Year-Olds :  H.  T.  Woolley.  The  Color 
Preferences  of  Five  Hundred  and  Fifty-Nine  Full-Blood  Indians: 
T.  R.  Garth.  A  Simple  Voice  Key :  F.  L.  Wells  and  J.  8.  Rooney. 
Results  of  Variations  in  Length  of  Memorized  Material :  E.  8.  Rob- 
inson and  W.  T.  Heron.  The  Stimulus  Error,  A  Reply:  8.  W. 
Fernberger. 

LA  CIENCIA  TOMISTA.  Ano  XIV,  Num.  LXXVIII.  Fundo 
Santo  Domingo  el  Rosario?  (cont.) :  L.  G.  Alonso-Getino.  De  ipsa 
philosophia  in  universum  secundum  doctrinam  aristolelico-thomis- 


JOURNALS  AND  NEW  BOOKS  719 

ticam    (cont.)  :  /.   M.  Ramirez.     Obras   de   Santa  Teresa:   J.   M. 
Aguado.     Cronica  del  movimiento  tomista:  V.  Beltran  de  Heredia. 

REVISTA  DE  FILOSOFIA.  Ano  VIII,  No.  VI.  Doctrinas  de  Levy- 
Briihl:  A.  N.  Ponce.  Alejandro  Venegas:  A.  Donoso.  La  Socio- 
logia  de  Francisco  Ramos  Mejia:  R.  A.  Orgaz.  Scalabrini  y  el 
comtismo :  V.  Mercante.  La  filosof ia  en  el  Ecuador  colonial :  E.  P. 
Barrera.  Las  revoluciones  francisa  y  rusa:  G.  S.  Moreau.  Evolu- 
cion  ideologica  de  Costa  Rica:  L.  F.  Gonzalez.  Por  la  Union 
Latino- Americana :  J.  Ingenieros. 

REVUE  DBS  SCIENCES  PHILOSOPHIQUES  ET  THEOLOGIQUES.  ll«me 
Annee,  No.  4.  Les  Arguments  de  M.  Einstein:  F.  Vial.  La 
"mine"  des  dantologues:  P.  Mandonnet.  Bulletin  de  Philosophic 
Sociale.  Bulletin  d'Histoire  de  la  Philosophic.  Bulletin  de  The- 
ologie  Speculative. 

LOGOS.  Anno  V,  Fascicolo  3-4.  II  cammino  della  conoscenza 
filosofica :  Jakovenko.  La  volatilizzazione  di  Dio :  Rensi.  II  prob- 
lema  delle  azioni  a  distanza :  Ranzoli.  Le  positivisme  mystique  de 
1'Inde:  Masson-Oursel.  Le  antinomic  della  valutazione:  Delia 
Valle.  II  sonno  in  psichiatria:  Epifanio.  La  teoria  di  Einstein  e 
il  f enomenismo :  Guastella.  Bergson  e  lo  spiritualismo  francese  del 
sec.  XIX :  Serini. 

THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CLINIC.  Vol.  XIV,  Nos.  5-6.  The  Analyt- 
ical Diagnosis :  L.  Witmer.  Miss  Inconsistency :  A.  M.  Jones.  An 
Analytical  Study  of  the  Intelligence  of  a  Group  of  Adolescent  De- 
liquent  Girls:  A.  8.  Starr.  The  Increase  of  the  Intelligence  Quo- 
tient through  Training :  G.  G.  Ide.  Children  Applying  for  Working 
Certificates:  R.  E.  Learning.  Eighteen  Children  from  an  Ortho- 
genie  Backward  Class:  C.  Easby.  Diagnostic  Teaching:  Albert — A 
Lazy  Boy :  W.  B.  Stewart.  A  Contrast  in  Efficiency :  H.  W.  Brown. 

Brunschvicg,  Leon:  L 'Experience  Humaine  et  la  Causalite 
Physique.  Paris :  Felix  Alcan.  1922.  xvi  -f-  625  pp. 

Dibble,  Charles  Lemuel :  A  Grammar  of  Belief.  Milwaukee : 
Morehouse  Publishing  Co.  1922.  208  pp. 

Ericksen,  Ephraim  Edward:  The  Psychological  and  Ethical 
Aspects  of  Mormon  Group  Life.  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago 
Press.  1922.  x  + 101  pp.  $1.50. 

Hjort,  Johan:  The  Unity  of  Science.  A  Sketch.  New  York: 
Knopf.  1922.  176  pp.  $2.50. 

Morgan,  Victor :  La  Voic  du  Chevalier.  Education  Experimen- 
tale  par  Soi-meme.  Nimes:  Imprimerie  Cooperative  "La  Labori- 
euse."  1922.  xxxvii  +  248  pp. 


720  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Miiller-Freienfels,  Richard:  Irrationalismus  Umrisse  einer 
Erkenntnislehre.  Leipzig :  Felix  Meiner.  1922.  viii  -f  300  pp. 
$1.60. 

Mumford,  Lewis:  The  Story  of  Utopias.  With  an  Introduc- 
tion by  Hendrik  Van  Loon.  New  York :  Boni  and  Liveright.  1922. 
xii  -|-  315  pp. 

Phelps,  William  Lyon:  Human  Nature  in  the  Bible.  New 
York:  Charles  Scribner's  Sons.  1922.  xii  +  333  pp. 

Papers  in  Honor  of  Josiah  Royce  on  his  Sixtieth  Birthday.  Re- 
printed from  Vol.  XXV,  No.  3  (May  1916),  of  The  Philosophical 
Review.  294  pp. 

Walston,  Charles,  (Waldstein) :  Harmonism  and  Conscious 
Evolution.  New  York :  Macmillan  Co.  1922.  xvi  -f  463  pp. 
$6.00.  

NOTES  AND  NEWS 

We  give  below  the  programme  of  the  joint  meeting  of  the  East- 
ern and  Western  Divisions  of  the  American  Philosophical  Associa- 
tion, which  will  be  held  at  Union  Theological  Seminary,  New  York 
City,  on  December  27,  28,  and  29,  1922.  All  sessions,  except  as 
otherwise  indicated,  will  be  held  in  Room  207.  The  public  is  in- 
vited to  attend  all  morning  and  afternoon  sessions  of  the  Associa- 
tion, except  the  business  meetings,  which  are  for  members  only. 
The  Smoker  and  Annual  Dinner  are  for  members  of  the  Association 
and  their  guests. 

WEDNESDAY,  DECEMBER  27 

9:30  A.M. 

Obscurantism  of  Science Harvey  O.  Townsend 

The  Metaphysics  of  Modern  Scepticism  J.  Loewenberg 

The  Metaphors  of  the  Reason H.  B.  Alexander 

A  Pragmatic  Conception  of  the  A  Priori Clarence  I.  Lewis 

3 :00  P.M. 

Paul  Carus  Lecture :  Existence  as  Stable  and  as  Precarious, 

John  Dewey 
THURSDAY,  DECEMBER  28 

9 :30  A.M. 

The  Moral  Criterion  in  Plato R.  C.  Lodge 

Amor  Dei  Intellectualis  Morris  R.  Cohen 

Origin  and  Value :  The  Unintelligibility  of  Philosophic  Modernism, 

Wilbur  M.  Urban 


NOTES  AND  NEWS  721 

2:00  P.M. 

Business  Meeting  of  the  Eastern  Division         (Room  207) 
Business  Meeting  of  the  "Western  Division         (Room  307) 

3  :00  P.M. 

Paul  Carus  Lecture :   Existence,  Ends,  and  Appreciation, 

John  Dewey 
7:00  P.M. 

(At  the  Commodore  Hotel,  West  Ball  Room) 

The  Annual  Dinner  of  the  Association 

"Welcome  by  President  McGiffert 

Address  by  the  President  of  the  Eastern  Division : 

The  Problem  of  Progress  Walter  G.  Everett 

FRIDAY,  DECEMBER  29 
9 :30  A.M. 

Paul  Carus  Lecture :  Existence,  Means,  and  Knowledge, 

John  Dewey 
10 :30  A.M. 

(In  Room  207) 

On  an  Inconsistency  in  Russell's  Treatment  of  Mental  Action, 

G.  Watts  Cunningham 

Giving  a  Name  to  Ignorance Theodore  de  Laguna 

The  Mind-Body  Impasse  Durant  Drake 

The  Emergent  Theory  of  Mind G.T.W.  Patrick 

10 :30  A.M. 
(In  Room  307) 

The  Philosophy  of  Feeling  in  Current  Poetics.    Katherine  E.  Gilbert 
(Introduced  by  Walter  G.  Everett) 

Philosophy  and  American  Law  Philip  L.  Given 

The  Rational  Character  of  the  Democratic  Principle, 

Marie  Collins  Swabey 

Frequency  of  Practice A.  P.  Brogan 

Papers  are  limited  to  twenty  minutes,  and  comments  on  papers 
to  ten  minutes. 


A  limited  number  of  copies  of  the  Titchener  Commemorative 
Volume  are  left  in  stock.  Since  the  sales  to  date  have  more  than 
paid  the  costs  of  the  edition,  the  Committee  in  charge  of  publica- 


722  JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

tion  have  decided  to  offer  these  remaining  copies  to  psychologists  at 
the  reduced  price  of  two  dollars,  postpaid.  The  proceeds  of  their 
sale,  together  with  the  balance  already  in  hand,  will  be  funded, 
and  the  interest  will  presently  be  used  to  establish  a  prize  for 
meritorious  work  in  experimental  psychology. 

The  volume,  which  consists  of  337  pages  of  the  style  and  size  of 
the  pages  of  The  American  Journal  of  Psychology,  contains  eigh- 
teen studies  in  various  departments  of  psychology,  dedicated  to 
Professor  Titchener  by  colleagues  and  former  students  on  his  com- 
pletion of  twenty-five  years  of  service  to  Cornell  University. 

Orders  may  be  sent  to  D.  R.  Knight,  Morrill  Hall,  Cornell  Uni- 
versity, Ithaca,  N.  Y. 

M.  F.  WASHBUBN 
W.  B.  PILLSBURY 
K.  M.  DALLENBACH 


The  sixth  semi-annual  meeting  of  the  Southwest  Philosophical 
Association  took  place  on  Saturday,  November  llth,  at  the  Univer- 
sity of  Southern  California.  After  a  business  session,  in  which  it  was 
decided  to  continue  the  present  officers  and  to  enlarge  the  scope  of 
work  and  membership,  a  paper  on  "The  Concept  of  Independence  in 
the  New  Realism"  was  read  by  Dean  Rieber  of  the  University  of 
California,  Southern  Branch,  and  also  one  on  "The  Knowledge  of 
Other  Minds"  by  Dr.  Henry  Nelson  Wieman  of  Occidental  College. 

After  a  discussion  of  the  papers,  an  executive  committee  was 
appointed  to  consider  an  enlarged  scope  for  future  activity  of  the 
society.  This  committee  consists  of  Ralph  Tyler  Flewelling,  Uni- 
versity of  Southern  California,  President;  Henry  Nelson  Wieman, 
Occidental  College,  Secretary-Treasurer;  Bernard  C.  Ewer,  Pomona 
College;  Dean  C.  H.  Rieber  of  University  of  California,  Southern 
Branch ;  and  Dr.  Carl  S.  Patton,  Los  Angeles. 


723 


NAMES  OF   CONTRIBUTORS  ARE  PRINTED  IN   SMALL   CAPITALS 


ACKEKMAN,  H.  C. — The  Differentiating 
Principle  of  Religion,  317. 

ADLERBLUM,  NIMA  H. — Gollanez '  Trans- 
lation of  Dodi  Ve-Nechdi,  639. 

ALEXANDER,  H.  B. — Sortais's  La  Phi- 
losophie  moderne  depuis  Bacon  jus- 
qu'&  Leibniz,  137. 

American  Philosophical  Association — 
Eastern  Division,  The  Meeting  of. — 
HELEN  Huss  PARKHURST,  210. 

"Analysis  of  Mind,  The,"  Dr.  Schil- 
ler's Analysis  of. — BEETBAND  RUS- 
SELL, 645. 

Analysis  of  Reflective  Thought,  An. — 
JOHN  DEWET,  29. 

Ancient  Landmarks:  A  Comment  on 
Spiritualistic  Materialism,  The.— 
MAET  WHITON  CALKINS,  493. 

Andler's  Nietzsche,  sa  Vie  et  sa  Pen- 
see,  Vol.  II,  Vol.  III.— R.  M.  WEN- 
LET,  246,  385. 

Anti-Behaviorists,  An  Open  Letter  to 
the— W.  S.  HUNTER,  307. 

Aristotelian  Society,  1920-21,  Proceed- 
ings of  the. — H.  T.  COSTELLO,  414. 

Aristotle's  Politica,  CEconomica,  and 
Atheniensum  Respubliea,  Oxford 
Translation. — H.  W.  SCHNEIDEE,  331. 

Avey's  Readings  in  Philosophy. — JOHN 
M.  WAEBEKE,  641. 

AYEES,  C.  E. — Dewey's  Human  Nature 
and  Conduct,  469. 

Behavior    and    Purpose. — WILSON    D. 

WALLIS,  580. 
Behaviorism       and       Consciousness. — 

JAMES  BISSETT  PEATT,  596. 
and  the  Programme  of  Philosophy. 

— JAMES  L.  MUESELL,  549. 
Behavioristie  Account  of  the  Significant 

Symbol,  A. — GEOEGE  H.  MEAD,  157. 
Bibliotheca        Chemico-Mathematica. — 

MOEEIS  R.  COHEN,  275. 
BOAS,  GEOEGE. — Souilhe's  Etude  sur  le 
Terme  ATNAMIS    dans  les  Dialogues 
de  Platon,  332. 

BODE,  B.  H. — Critical  Realism,  68. 
BOGGS,    LUCINDA     PEABL. — A     Partial 

Analysis  of  Faith,  15. 
Brierley's  An  Introduction  to  Psy- 
chology, 666. 

Drever's  The  Psychology  of  Every- 
day Life,  and  The  Psychology  of 

industry,  249. 
BOSANQUET,    BEENABD.  — ' '  Implication 

and  Linear  Inference,"  292. 
Bosanquet's  The  Meeting  of  Extremes 
in  Contemporary  Philosophy. — J.  E. 
TUENER,  553. 

Boutroux,  Emile — (a  tribute). — JOHN 
H.  RANDALL,  JR.,  26. 


Boyer's  Christianisme  et  Neo-Platonis- 
me  dans  la  formation  de  Saint  Au- 
gustin  and  L'ldee  de  Verit6  dans  la 
Philosophie  de  Saint  Augustine. — C. 
C.  CLIFFORD,  49. 
BLANSHABD,  BEAND. — McTaggart's  The 

Nature  of  Existence,  497. 
BEEITWIESEE,  J.  V. — Korzybski's  The 

Manhood  of  Humanity,  301. 
Brierley's  An  Introduction  to  Psychol- 
ogy.— LUCINDA  PEARL  BOGGS,  666. 
BUSH,   WENDELL   T. — Esthetic    Values 

and  Their  Interpretation,  119. 
Levy-Bruhl's  La  Mentalit£  Primi- 
tive, and  Delacroix 's  La  Religion 
et  la  Foi,  694. 

More's  Platonism,   and    The  Reli- 
gion of  Plato,  558. 
Miinsterberg  's  Hugo  Miinsterberg, 

his  Life  and  his  Work,  642. 
The  Paris  Philosophical  Congress, 

241. 

Burthogge's  Philosophical  Writings. — 
STEELING  P.  LAMPBECHT,  243. 

CALKINS,  MAEY  WHITON. — The  Ancient 
Landmarks:  A  Comment  on  Spirit- 
ualistic Materialism,  493. 

Carr's  General  Principle  of  Relativity. 
— EDWAED  KASNEE,  220. 

Causality,  Dr.  McTaggart  and. — JOSH- 
UA C.  GEEGORY,  515. 

Character,  Measures  of  Intelligence  and. 

— A.    T.  POFFENBERGEB,   261. 

CLIFFORD,  C.  C. — Boyer's  Christianisme 
et  Neo-Platonisme  dans  la  forma- 
tion de  Saint  Augustin,  and  L  'Idee 
de  Verite  dans  la  Philosophie  de 
Saint  Augustine,  49. 
Garrigou-Lagrange's  Dieu,  son  Ex- 
istence et  sa  Nature,  52. 
COHEN,  MORRIS  R. — Bibliotheea  Chem- 
ico-Mathematica, 275. 
Complex  Dilemma,  The:    A  Rejoinder. 

— THEODOEE  DE  LAGUNA,  189. 
Concept  of  Sensation,  The. — JAMES  L. 

MUESELL,  684. 

Conference  on  Philosophy  at  the  Uni- 
versity of  Toronto. — JAMES  GIBSON 
HUME,  83. 

CONGER,  GEOEGE  P. — The  Implicit  Dual- 
ity of  Thinking,  225. 
Consciousness,  Behaviorism  and. — 

JAMES  BISSETT  PRATT,   596. 
Physical,  Is? — R.  W.  SELLARS,  690. 
Conybeare's  Russian  Dissenters. — CLAR- 
ENCE AUGUSTUS  MANNING,  270. 
Correspondence,  Truth  as:    A  Redefini- 
tion.— JAMES  L.  MUESELL,  181. 
Cosmology   of   William   James,   The. — 
HEBBEBT  NICHOLS,  673. 


724 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


COSTKLLO,  H.  T. — Proceedings  of  the 

Aristotelian  Society,  1920-21,  414. 
Cotton's  The  Defective  Delinquent  and 

the  Insane. — F.  L.  WELLS,  442. 
CREIGHTON,  J.  E.— The  Form  of  Philo- 
sophical Intelligibility,  253. 
Critu-al  Realism.— B.  H.  BODE,  68. 
And   the    External   World. — STIR- 
LINO  P.  LAMPRECHT,  651. 
Some  Logical  Aspects  of. — A.  W. 
MOORE,  589. 

Delacroix's  La  Religion  et  la  Foi. — W. 

T.  BUSH,  694. 

DE  LACUNA,  THEODORE. — Point,  Line  and 
Surface,  as  Sets  of  Solids,  449. 
Robb'a  The  Absolute  Relations  of 

Time  and  Space,  361. 
Rougier  's  Philosophy  and  the  New 

Physics,  389. 

The  Complex  Dilemma;  A  Rejoin- 
der, 189. 
The  Nature  of  Space — I,  II,  393, 

421. 
Democracy   and  Morals. — G.   A.   TAW- 

NEY  and  E.  L.  TALBERT,  141. 
DEMOS,  RAPHAEL. — Romanticism  vs.  the 

Worship  of  Facts,  197. 
Deutsche  Philosophic  der  Gegenwart  in 
Selbsdarstellungen,  Die. — JAMES  GUT- 
MANN,  304. 
Dewey's  The  Dalton  Laboratory  Plan. 

— I.  L.  KANDEL,  667. 
Dewey's  Human  Nature  and  Conduct. 

— 0.  E.  ATERS,  469. 
DEWIY,  JOHN. — An  Analysis  of  Reflec- 
tive Thought,  29. 
Knowledge   and   Speech   Reaction, 

561. 

Realism  without  Monism  or  Dual- 
ism—I,  II,  309,  351. 
Dichotomy    of    Nature,    The. — W.    H. 

SHELDON,  365. 
Differentiating   Principle    of    Religion, 

The. — H.  C.  ACKERMAN,  317. 

Distribution    in   Formal   Logic,   Doing 

without. — RAY  H.  DOTTERER,  462. 

Of  Terms,  Immediate  Inference  and 

the.— ALBERT  L.  HAMMOND,  124. 

Doing  without  Distribution  in  Formal 

Logic. — RAY  H.  DOTTERER,  462. 
DOTTERER,  RAY  H. — Doing  without  Dis- 
tribution in  Formal  Logic,  462. 
Drover's  The  Psychology  of  Everydaj 
Life    and    The    Psychology    of    In- 
dustry.— L.  PEARL  Booos.  249. 
Dualism,  Realism  without  Monism  or, 

I,  II. — JOHN  DEWEY,  309,  351. 
Duality  of   Thinking,  The  Implicit.— 

GEORGE  P.  CONGER,  225. 
DUNLAP,    KNIGHT. — The    Identity    of 

Instinct  and  Habit,  85. 

Dunlap's  Mysticism,  Freudianism  and 

Scientific  Psychology.— R.  8.  WOOD- 

WORTH,  101. 


EATON,    RALPH    M. — Smith's    Founda- 
tions of  Formal  Logic,  715. 
Emergent  Theory  of  Mind,  The. — G.  T. 

W.  PATRICK,  701. 
Empiricism,  Professor  Perry's. — H.  R. 

SMART,  570. 

Esthetic  Values  and  Their  Interpreta- 
tion.— WENDELL  T.  BUSH,  119. 
Esthetics,   A  Suggestion   Regarding. — 

STEPHEN  C.  PEPPER,  113. 
Two  Notes  on. — CHARLES  E.  WHIT- 
MORE,  708. 

Facts,  Romanticism  vs.  the  Worship  of. 
— RAPHAEL  DEMOS,  197. 

Faith,  A  Partial  Analysis  of. — Lu- 
CINDA  PEARL  Booos,  15. 

Fiske  Re-Anticipated. — WILLIAM  ERN- 
EST HOCKING,  441. 

Fiske 's  Theory  regarding  the  Value  of 
Infancy,  An  Historical  Anticipation 
of. — WESLEY  RAYMOND  WELLS,  208. 

FLETCHER,  JEFFERSON  B. — Gilson's  Le 
Thomisme,  78. 

Form  of  Philosophical  Intelligibility, 
The. — J.  E.  CREIGHTON,  253. 

FUNG,  TU-LAN. — Shuming  's  Eastern 
and  Western  Cultures  and  their 
Philosophies.  611. 

Garrigou-Lagrange 's  Dieu,  son  Exist- 
ence et  sa  Nature. — C.  C.  CLIFFORD, 
52. 

GEIGER,  J.  R. — Must  We  Give  Up  In- 
stincts in  Psychology,  94. 

GIDDINGS,  FRANKLIN  H. — The  Grounds 
of  Presumption,  617. 

Gilson's  Le  Thomisme. — JEFFERSON  B. 
FLETCHER,  78. 

Gollanez'  Translation  of  Dodi  Ve-Nech- 
di   (Uncle  and  Nephew). — NIMA  H. 
ADLERBLUM,  639. 

GREGORY,  JOSHUA  C. — Dr.  McTaggart 
and  Causality,  515. 

Grounds  of  Presumption,  The. — FRANK- 
LIN H.  GIDDINGS,  617. 

GUTMANN,  JAMES. — Die  Deutsche  Philo- 
sophic der  Gegenwart  in  Selbsdarstel- 
lungen, 304. 

Habit,  The  Identity  of  Instinct  and. — 
KNIGHT  DUNLAP,  85. 

Haldane's  The  Reign  of  Relativity. — 
J.  E.  TURNER,  191. 

Hall's  Senescence.— H.  L.  HOLLING- 
WORTH,  525. 

HAMMOND,  ALBERT  L. — Immediate  In- 
ference and  the  Distribution  of 
Terms,  124. 

Hayes'  Sociology  and  Ethics. — JOHN 
WARBEKE,  444. 

Historical  Anticipation  of  John  Fiske 's 
Theory  regarding  the  Value  of  In- 
fancy, An. — WESLEY  RAYMOND 
WELLS,  208. 


INDEX 


725 


HOCKING,  WILLIAM  ERNEST. — Fiske  Re- 
Anticipated,  441. 

HOLLINGWORTH,  H.  L. — Hall's  Sene- 
scence, 525. 

Hudson's  The  Truths  We  Live  By. — 
MARY  SHAW,  501. 

HUME,  JAMES  GIBSON. — Conference  on 
Philosophy  at  the  University  of  To- 
ronto, 83. 

Hume's  Translation  of  the  Thirteen 
Principal  Upanishads. — JAMES  Bis- 
SETT  PRATT,  528. 

HUNTER,  W.  S. — An  Open  Letter  to  the 

Anti-Behaviorists,  307. 
The  Modification  of  Instinct,  98. 

Hurst's  The  Psychology  of  the  Special 
Senses  and  their  Functional  Dis- 
orders.— A.  T.  POFPENBERGES,  24. 

Identity  of  Instinct  and  Habit,  The. — 

KNIGHT  DUNLAP,  85. 
Immediate  Inference  and  the  Distribu- 
tion   of    Terms. — ALBERT    L.    HAM 
MONO,  124. 
"Implication  and  Linear   Inference." 

— BERNARD  BOSANQUET,  292. 
Implicit  Duality  of   Thinking,   The.— 

GEORGE  P.  CONGER,  225. 
Infancy  in  Eighteenth-century  Thought, 
The  Length  of  Human. — ARTHUR 
O.  LOVE  JOT,  381. 

An  Historical  Anticipation  of 
John  Fiske 's  Theory  regarding 
the  Value  of. — WESLEY  RAY- 
MOND WELLS,  208. 

Inference  and  the  Distribution  of 
Terms,  Immediate. — ALBERT  L. 
HAMMOND,  124. 

"Implication  and  Linear." — BER- 
NARD BOSANQUET,  292. 
Instinct  and  Habit,  The  Identity  of. — 

KNIGHT  DUNLAP,  85. 
The  Modification  of. — WALTER  S. 

HUNTER,  98. 
Instincts  in  Psychology,  Must  We  Give 

Up. — J.  R.  GEIGER,  94. 
Integration,  The  Word,  and  a  Few  Re- 
marks on  the  Paleontology  of  Words. 
— WILLIAM  E.  RITTER,  266. 
Intellect,  Intelligence  and. — A.  A.  Ro- 

BACK,  325. 
Intelligence    and    Character,    Measures 

Of. — A.    T.    PorFENBERGER,    261. 

And  Intellect. — A.  A.  ROBACK,  325. 

Intelligibility,  The  Form  of  Philosoph- 
ical.— J.  E.  CREIGHTON,  253. 

Is  Consciousness  Physical? — R.  W. 
SELLARS,  690. 

James   and   Lange's   The   Emotions. — 

JOHN  M.  WARBEKE,  641. 
James,   The  Cosmology  of  William. — 

HERBERT  NICHOLS,  673. 
Journals  and  New  Books,  25,  55,   82, 

110,    139,    166,    195,    223,    250,    276, 


306,  334,  363,  390,  418,  447,  475, 
503,  531,  558,  587,  614,  642,  669, 
698,  718. 

KANDEL,   I.   L. — Dewey's   The   Dalton 

Laboratory  Plan,  667. 
KANTOR,  J.   R. — Memory,   A  Triphase 

Objective  Action,  624. 
The  Nervous  System,  Psychological 

Fact  or  Fiction,  38. 
KASNER,   EDWARD. — Carr's   General 
Principle     of     Relativity;     Schliek's 
Space    and    Time    in    Contemporary 
Physics;    Sampson's  On  Gravitation 
and  Relativity,  220. 
Knowledge    and     Speech     Reaction. — 

JOHN  DEWEY,  561. 
Of  Other  Minds. — HEXRY  NELSON 

WlEMAN,   605. 

Korzybski's  The  Manhood  of  Human- 
ity.— J.  V.  BREITWIESSER,  301. 

LAMPRECHT,  STERLING  P. — Burthogge's 

Philosophical  Writings,  243. 
Critical  Realism  and  the  External 

World,  651. 

The   Metaphysical  Status   of   Sen- 
sations, 169. 
Langf eld's    The    Esthetic    Attitude.— 

HELEN  H.  PAKHURST,  717. 
LANGFELD,     H.     S. — Muller-Freienf  els ' 

Psychologie  der  Kunst,  664. 
Length  of   Human   Infancy  in  Eight- 
eenth-century    Thought,     The. — AR- 
THUR O.  LOVEJOY,  381. 
Levy-Bruhl's  La  Mentalite  Primitive. — 

W.  T.  BUSH,  694. 
"Linear  Inference,  Implication  and." 

— BERNARD  BOSANQUET,  292. 
Logic,   Doing   without   Distribution  in 

Formal. — RAY  H.  DOTTERER,  462. 
LOVEJOY,  ARTHUR  O. — Pragmatism  and 

the  New  Materialism,  5. 
The  Length  of  Human  Infancy  in 
Eighteenth-century  Thought,  381. 
Time,     Meaning     and     Transcend- 
ence—I,  II,  505,  533. 

McTaggart's  The  Nature  of  Existence. 

— BRAND  BLANSHARD,  497. 
McTaggart  and  Causality,  Dr. — JOSHUA 

C.  GREGORY,  515. 
MANNING,  CLARENCE  AUGUSTUS. — Cony- 

beare's  Russian  Dissenters,  270. 
Materialism,     Pragmatism,     and     the 

New. — ARTHUR  O.  LOVEJOY,  5. 
The  Ancient  Landmarks:    A  Com- 
ment    on     Spiritualistic. — MARY 
WHITON  CALKINS,  493. 
The  New. — JAMES  BISSETT  PRATT, 

337. 

MEAD,  GEORGE  H. — A  Behavioristic 
Account  of  the  Significant  Symbol, 
157. 


726 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


Meaning  and  Transcendence,  Time — I, 

II. — ARTHUR  O.  LOVEJOY,  505,  533. 

Measures  of  Intelligence  and  Character. 

— A.   T.   POFFENBERGER,   261. 

Mechanical     Order,     Mind     in     the. — 

HENRY  BRADFORD  SMITH,  489. 
MECKLIN,  JOHN  M. — Ross's  The  Prin- 
ciples of  Sociology,  216 
Memory:   A  Triphase  Objective  Action. 

— J.  B.  KANTOR,  624. 
MERRILL,  A.  A. — The  t  of  Physics,  238. 
Metaphysical  Status  of  Sensations,  The. 

— STERLING  P.  LAMPRECHT,  169. 
Metaphysician's     Petitio,     A. — Q.     A. 

TAWNEY,  407. 
Metaphysics,     On     the    Method     of. — 

CHARLES  H.  TOLL,  57. 
Mind  in  the  Mechanical  Order. — HENRY 

BRADFORD  SMITH,  489. 
The  Emergent  Theory  of. — G.  T. 

W.  PATRICK,  701. 
Minds,   Knowledge   of   Other. — HENRY 

NELSON  WIEMAN,  605. 
Modification  of  Instinct,  The. — WALTER 

8.  HUNTER,  98. 
Monism  or  Dualism,  Realism  without — 

I,  II.— JOHN  DEWEY,  309,  351. 
MOORE,  A.  W. — Some  Logical  Aspects 

of  Critical  Realism,  589. 
Morals,  Democracy  and. — G.  A.  TAW- 
NEY and  E.  L.  TALBERT,  141. 
More's  The  Religion  of  Plato. — W.  T. 

BUSH,  557. 

Platonism. — W.  T.  BUSH,  557. 
Miiller-Freienf  els '      Psychologic      d  e  r 

Kunst. — H.  S.  LANGFELD,  664. 
MUNRO,  THOMAS. — The  Verification  of 

Standards  of  Value,  294. 
Munsterberg 's  Hugo  Miinsterberg,  His 
Life  and  His  Work. — W.  T.  BUSH, 
642. 

MUBSELL,  JAMES  L. — Behaviorism  and 
the  Programme  of  Philosophy, 
549. 

The  Concept  of  Sensation,  684. 
Russell's    The    Analysis    of   Mind, 

163. 

Truth  as  Correspondence:     A  Re- 
definition, 181. 

Mast  We  Give  Up  Instinct  in  Psychol- 
ogy?— J.  R.  GEIGER,  94. 

Nature  of  Space,  The — I,  II. — THEO 

DORK  DE  LAGUNA,  393,  421. 
The  Dichotomy  of. — W.  H.  SHEL- 
DON, 365. 
New    Materialism,    The. — JAMES    BlS- 

srrr  PRATT,  337. 
Nervous  System,  Psychological  Fact  or 

Fiction  f.  The. — J*.  R.  KANTOR,  38. 
NICHOLS,  HERBERT. — The  Cosmology  of 

William  James,  673. 
Notes  and  News,  26.  56.  82,  111,  140. 
167,    195,    224,    251,    277,    307,    339, 
364,    392,    419,    448,   476,    504,    532, 
560,  588,  615,  644,  671,  699,  720. 


On     the     Method     of     Metaphysics. — 
CHARLES  H.  TOLL,  57. 

Paleontology  of  Words,  The  Word  In- 
tegration,  and   a   Few   Remarks   on 
the. — WILLIAM  E.  RITTER,  266. 
Paris    Philosophical    Congress,    The.— 

W.  T.  BUSH,  241. 
Parker's  The  Principles  of  Esthetics. — 

HELEN  Huss  PARKHURST,  81. 
PARKHURST,     HELEN     H. — Langf  eld 's 

The  Esthetic  Attitude,  717. 
The  Meeting  of  the  American  Philo- 
sophical      Association — Eastern 
Division,  210. 

Parker's  The  Principles  of  Esthe- 
tics, 81. 
Partial    Analysis    of    Faith,    A. — Lu- 

CINDA  PEARL  BOGGS,  15. 
PATRICK,  G.  T.  W. — The  Emergent  The- 
ory of  Mind,  701. 

PEPPER,  STEPHEN  C. — A  Suggestion  Re- 
garding Esthetics,  113. 
Perry 's  Empiricism,  Professor. — H.  R. 

SMART,  570. 
Petitio,     A     Metaphysician's. — G.     A. 

TAWNEY,  407. 

Philosophical  Association — E  astern 
Division,  The  Meeting  of  the  Ameri- 
can.— HELEN  Huss  PARKHURST,  210. 
Philosophy,  Behaviorism  and  the  Pro- 
gramme of. — JAMES  L.  MURSELL, 
549. 

Physics,  The  t  of.— A.  A.  MERRILL,  238. 
PICARD,  MAURICE. — Sellar's  Evolution- 
ary Naturalism,  582. 
Value  and  Worth,  477. 
Picard's  Values,  Immediate  and  Con- 
tributory.— WILBUR  M.  URBAN,  53. 
PILLSBURY,  W.  B. — Woodworth's  Psy- 
chology, 446. 

POFFENBERGER,  A.  T. — Hurst 's  The  Psy- 
chology of  the  Special  Senses  and 
their  Functional  Disorders,  24. 
Measures  of  Intelligence  and  Char- 
acter, 261. 

Point,   Line   and    Surface,   as   Sets   of 

Solids. — THEODORE  DE  LAGUXA,  449. 

Pragmatism  and  the  New  Materialism. 

— ARTHUR  O.  LOVEJOY,  5. 
PRATT,    JAMES    BISSETT. — Behaviorism 

and  Consciousness,  596. 
Hume's  Translation  of  the  Thirteen 

Principles  Upanishads,  528. 
The  New  Materialism,  337. 
Predicate  Term,  The. — JOHN  J.  TOOHEY, 

542. 

Presumption,  The  Grounds  of. — FRANK- 
LIN H.  GIDDINGS,  617. 
Professor  Perry's  Empiricism. — H.   R. 

SMART,  570. 

Psychology,    Must    We    Give    Up    In- 
stincts int — J.  R.  GEIGER,  94. 
Mr.  Russell's. — F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 
281. 


INDEX 


727 


Purpose,  Behavior  and. — WILSON  D. 
WALLIS,  580. 

RANDALL,  JOHN   H.  JR. — Emile  Bout- 

roux,  26. 

Kealism,  Critical.— B.  H.  BODE,  68. 
Critical     and     External     World. — 

STEELING  P.  LAMPRECHT,  651. 
Dr.  A.  N.  Whitehead's  Scientific.— 

J.  E.  TURNER,  146. 
Some  Logical  Aspects  of  Critical. 

—A.  W.  MOORE,  589. 
Without    Monism    or    Dualism. — I, 

II,— JOHN  DEWEY,  309,  351. 
Reflective  Thought,  An  Analysis  of. — 

JOHN  DEWEY,  29. 

Relativity,  Old  and  New. — H.  A.  WAD- 
MAN,  200. 
"Relativity,    Old    and    New."— J.    E. 

TURNER,  661. 
Religion,  The  Differentiating  Principle 

Of. — H.  C.  ACKERMAN,  317. 

HITTER,  WILLIAM  E. — The  Word  Integ- 
ration, and  a  Few  Remarks  on  the 
Paleontology  of  Words,  266. 

ROBACK,  A.  A. — Intelligence  and  In- 
tellect, 325. 

Robb's  The  Absolute  Relations  of  Time 
and  Space. — THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA, 
361. 

Romanticism  vs.  the  Worship  of  Facts. 
— RAPHAEL  DEMOS,  197. 

Ross's  The  Principles  of  Sociology. — 
JOHN  M.  MECKLIN,  216. 

Rougier's  Philosophy  and  the  New 
Physics. — THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA,  389. 

RUSSELL,  BERTRAND. — Dr.  Schiller 's 
Analysis  of  ' '  The  Analysis  of  Mind, ' ' 
645. 

Russell's    Psychology,    Mr. — F.    C.    S. 

SCHILLER,  281. 

The  Analysis  of  Mind. — JAMES  L. 
MURSELL,  163. 

Sampson's  On  Gravitation  and  Rela- 
tivity.— EDWARD  KASNER,  220. 

SCHILLER,  F.  C.  S.— Mr.  Russell's  Psy- 
chology, 281. 

Schiller 's  Analysis  of  ' '  The  Analysis  of 
Mind, ' '  Dr. — BERTRAND  RUSSELL, 
645. 

Schlick's  Space  and  Time  in  Contempo- 
rary Physics. — EDWARD  KASNER,  220. 

SCHNEIDER,  H.  W. — Oxford  Translation 
of  Aristotle's  Politics,  (Economica, 
and  Atheniensum  Respublica,  331. 

Scientific  Realism,  Dr.  A.  N.  White- 
head's. — J.  E.  TURNER,  146. 

SELLARS,  R.  W. — Is  Consciousness  Phys- 
ical!, 690. 

Sellars '  Evolutionary  Naturalism. — 
MAURICE  PICARD,  582. 

Sensation,  The  Concept  of. — JAMES  L. 
MURSELL,  684. 

Sensations,  The  Metaphysical  Status  of. 
— STERLING  P.  LAMPRECHT,  169. 


SHAW,  MAEY. — Hudson's  The  Truths 
We  Live  By,  501. 

SHELDON,  W.  H. — The  Dichotomy  of 
Nature,  365. 

Shuming's  Eastern  and  Western  Cul- 
tures and  their  Philosophies. — YU-LAN 
FUNG,  611. 

Significant  Symbol,  A  Behavioristic  Ac- 
count of  the. — GEORGE  H.  MEAD,  157. 

SMART,  H.  R. — Professor  Perry's  Em- 
piricism, 570. 

SMITH,  HENRY  BRADFORD. — Mind  in  the 
Mechanical  Order,  489. 

Smith's  Foundations  of  Formal  Logic. 
— RALPH  M.  EATON,  715. 

Some  Logical  Aspects  of  Critical  Real- 
ism.— A.  W.  MOORE,  589. 

Solids,  Point,  Line  and  Surface  as  Sets 
of. — THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA,  449. 

Sortais  's  La  Philosophie  moderne  depuis 
Bacon  jusqu  '&  Leibniz. — H.  B.  ALEX- 
ANDER, 137. 

Souilhe's  Etude  sur  le  Terme  ATNAMIZ 
dans  les  Dialogues  de  Platon. — 
GEORGE  BOAS,  332. 

Space,  The  Nature  of, — I,  II.— THEO- 
DORE DE  LAGUNA,  393,  421. 

Speech  Reaction,  Knowledge  and. — 
JOHN  DEWEY,  561. 

Suggestion  Regarding  Esthetics,  A. — 
STEPHEN  C.  PEPPER,  113. 

Surface,  Point,  Line  and,  as  Sets  of 
Solids. — THEODORE  DE  LAGUNA,  449. 

Symbol,  A  Behavioristie  Account  of 
the  Significant. — GEORGE  H.  MEAD, 
157. 

T   of   Physics,    The.— A.   A.    MERRILL, 

238. 
T  ALBERT,  E.  L.  and  G.  A.  TAWNEY. — 

Democracy  and  Morals,  141. 
TAWNEY,  G.  A.  and  E.  L.  TALBERT. — 

Democracy  and  Morals,  141. 
TAWNEY,    G.    A. — A    Metaphysician's 

Petitio,  407. 
Term,  The  Predicate. — JOHN  J.  TOOHEY, 

542. 
Terms,   Immediate    Inference    and    the 

Distribution    of. — ALBERT    L.    HAM- 
MOND, 124. 
Thinking,   The   Implicit   Duality   of. — 

GEORGE  P.  CONGER,  225. 
Time,  Meaning  and  Transcendence — I, 

II. — ARTHUR  O.  LOVEJOY,  505,  533. 
TOLL,  CHARLES  H. — On  the  Method  of 

Metaphysics,  57. 
TOOHEY,  JOHN  J. — The  Predicate  Term, 

542. 
Toronto,  Conference  on  Philosophy  at 

the    University    of. — JAMES    GIBSON 

HUME,  83. 
Transcendence,  Time,  Meaning  and, — I, 

II. — ARTHUR  O.  LOVEJOY,  505,  533. 
Truth  as  Correspondence:   A  Redefini- 
tion.— JAMES  L.  MURSELL,  181. 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY 


TURNER,  J.  E.— < '  Relativity.  Old   and 

New/' 661. 

TURNER,  J.  E.— Bosanquet  '•  The  Meet- 
ing of  Extremes  in  Contemporary 
Philosophy,  553. 

"Relativity,  Old  and  New,"  661. 
Dr.   A.   N.  Whitehead's   Scientific 

Realism,  146. 
Haldane's  The  Reign  of  Relativity, 

191. 

Two  Notes  on  Esthetics. — CHARLES  E. 
WHITMORE,  708. 

URBAN,  WILBUR  M. — Picard's  Values, 
Immediate  and  Contributory,  53. 

Value   and   Worth. — MAURICE   PICARD, 

477. 
The  Verification  of  Standards  of. 

— THOMAS  MUNRO,  294. 
Values  and  Their  Interpretation,  Esthe- 
tic.— WENDELL  T.  BUSH,  119. 
Verification  of  Standards  of  Value. — 
THOMAS  MUNRO,  294. 

WADMAN,  H.  A. — Relativity,  Old  and 
New,  200. 

WALLIS,  WILSON  D. — Behavior  and  Pur- 
pose, 580. 

WARBEKE,  JOHN  M. — Avey's  Readings 
in  Philosophy,  641. 


James  and  Lange's,  The  Emotions 

641. 
Hayes'  Sociology  and  Ethics,  444. 

WILLS,  F.  L. — Cotton's  The  Defective 
Delinquent  and  the  Insane,  442. 

WELLS,  WESLEY  RAYMOND. — An  His- 
torical Anticipation  of  John  Fiske's 
Theory  regarding  the  Value  of  In- 
fancy, 208. 

WENLEY,  R.  M.— Andler's  Nietzsche, 
sa  Vie  et  sa  Pensee,  Vol.  II,  Vol.  III. 
246,  385. 

Whitehead's  Scientific  Realism,  Dr.  A. 
N.— J.  E.  TURNER,  146. 

WHITMORE,  CHARLES  E. — Two  Notes  on 
Esthetics,  708. 

WIEMAN,  HENRY  NELSON. — Knowledge 
of  Other  Minds,  605. 

WOODWORTH,  R.  S. — Dunlap's  Mysti- 
cism, Freudianism  and  Scientific  Psy- 
chology, 101. 

Woodworth  's  Psychology. — W.  B. 
PILLSBURY,  446. 

Word  Integration,  and  a  Few  Remarks 
on  the  Paleontology  of  Words,  The. 
— WILLIAM  E.  RIOTER,  266. 

Worth,  Value  and. — MAURICE  PICARD, 
477. 

Worship  of  Facts,  Romanticism  vs. — 
RAPHAEL  DEMOS,  197. 


I 


B     The  Journal  of  Philosophy 

1 
J6 

v.19 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 


UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO 
LIBRARY 


w  : 


ill