Skip to main content

Full text of "Kant's critical philosophy for English readers"

See other formats


KANT'S    CRITICAL   PHILOSOPHY 


V^\J 

<] 


KANT'S 
CRITICAL  PHILOSOPHY 


FOR    ENGLISH    READERS 


BY 


JOHN   P.   MAHAFFY,  D.D. 

FELLOW    AND    TUTOR    OF    TRINITY    COLLEGE,    DUBLIN 
PROFESSOR   OF   ANCIENT    HISTORY   IN    THE   UNIVERSITY   OF    DUBLIN 


JOHN    H.    BERNARD,    B.D. 

FELLOW   OF   TRINITY   COLLEGE,  DUBLIN 
ARCHBISHOP   KING'S   LECTURER    IN    DIVINITY    IN    THE   UNIVERSITY   OF   DUBLIN 


A  NEW  AND   COMPLETED  EDITION 


VOL.  II. 
THE  PROLEGOMENA  TRANSLATED,  WITH  NOTES  AND 


VANNEVAR  &  co 

438  YONGE  STREET. 

ILon&on 

MACMILLAN    AND    CO. 

AND    NEW    YORK 
I  889 


All  rights  resented 


PREFACE 

THE  following  translation  of  Kant's  Prolegomena  to 
any  Future  Metaphysic  is  not  the  first  which  has  been 
laid  before  the  English  public.  Richardson  published 
a  translation  in  i  8  I  8,  which  is  now  so  rare  that  Mr. 
Lewes,  though  his  knowledge  of  this  sort  of  literature 
was  exceedingly  wide,  seemed  to  be  unaware  of  its  ex 
istence.1  When  I  had  completed  part  of  the  task,  I 
chanced  to  find  a  copy  of  this  book,  which  is  full  of 
errors  and  inaccuracies,  but  yet  has  merit  enough  to 
have  escaped  oblivion,  had  the  author  published -it  at  a 
time  when  anything  whatever  was  known  in  England 
about  Kant's  philosophy.  I  was  tempted  to  use  it 
in  some  sections  as  the  basis  of  the  present  work,  in 
order  to  relieve  myself  of  the  tedium  of  writing  out 
the  whole  translation.  But  so  many  corrections 
were  necessary  that  it  hardly  saved  me  any  trouble, 
and  probably  my  book  may  not  have  been  improved 
by  putting  the  new  wine  into  the  old  bottles.  Still 
I  am  answerable  for  the  general  correctness  of  the 

1  Hist,  of  Phil.  ii.  p.  441,  note. 


vi  PREFACE 


following  translation,  and  believe  that,  clumsy  as  it 
may  be,  it  is  far  more  readable  than  Kant's  original. 
There  are  at  least  twice  as  many  full  stops  as  in  the 
German  ;  sundry  missing  verbs  and  pronouns  have 
been  supplied,  and  I  have  done  what  I  could  to 
make  the  terms  more  precise  without  damaging  the 
faithfulness  of  the  reproduction. 

There  is  also  recently  published  a  good  version 
by  Mr.  Bax,  who  had  the  advantage  of  using  the 
First  Edition  of  the  present  work,  which  appeared 
in  1872. 

I  need  say  nothing  here  of  the  scope  of  the 
Prolegomena,  as  Kant  himself  has  explained  it  in  his 
Introduction,  but  lay  special  stress  on  the  fact,  that 
while  prior  in  time  to  the  Second  Edition  of  the 
Kritik,  and  professedly  expounding  the  First  Edition, 
its  attitude  is  completely  that  of  the  Second  Edition 
on  the  great  question  of  idealism.  When  Schopen 
hauer's  school  talk  of  Kant's  supposed  change  of 
opinion  between  1781  and  1787,  they  should  be 
reminded  that  in  1783  he  wrote  the  Prolegomena, 
not  to  refute,  but  to  explain  his  original  Kritik,  and 
that  in  no  work  has  he  spoken  out  more  precisely 
against  absolute  idealism. 

Most  of  the  terms  used  do  not  require  any 
special  explanation,  but  the  following  points  may 
be  worth  noticing.  As  in  Vol.  L,  knowledge  and 
cognition  are  both  used,  and  used  synonymously,  on 
account  of  the  convenience  and  precision  of  the 


PREFACE  vil 


forms  cognitive  and  cognise,  while  the  Saxon  word  is 
clearer  to  most  readers.  I  have  frequently  printed 
the  word  Reason  with  a  capital,  where  it  means  a 
special  faculty,  as  distinguished  from  the  under 
standing,  but  as  Kant  himself  often  passes  back  to 
the  wider  meaning,  it  was  impossible  to  distinguish 
all  the  individual  occurrences  of  the  more  special 
meaning  and  to  do  more  than  call  attention  to  the 
distinction.  In  the  case  of  another  word  I  have 
taken  a  liberty  which  appears  to  be  an  improvement 
on  the  original.  While  Kant  uses  Begriff  as  synony 
mous  with  our  concept,  he  also  uses  it  for  those 
vaguer  mental  representations  which  are  under  no 
category,  as,  for  example,  God  and  Infinity.  In 
these  cases  I  have  used  the  word  notion,  as  being 
vaguer  than  concept,  and  may  call  the  reader's  atten 
tion  to  the  curious  fact  that  the  Germans  are  not 
supplied  with  a  special  word  to  indicate  a  vaguer 
thought  than  a  concept.  Kant's  Vorstellnng  includes 
intuitions,  his  Idee  has  a  quite  special  meaning. 

Apart  from  nomenclature,  I  have  in  many 
places  endeavoured  to  bring  out  the  point  of  the 
argument,  by  trifling  additions  or  modifications — 
so  trifling  that  they  will  not  appear  without  a 
careful  comparison  with  the  original.  It  was 
indeed  suggested  to  me  in  some  of  these  places  to 
translate  quite  literally,  and  leave  the  reader  to 
solve  the  difficulty  left  by  Kant.  This  indeed  is 
the  plan  followed  by  Mr.  Bax.  But  I  venture  to 


viii  PREFACE 


hope  that  nowhere  has  the  sense  of  the  original 
been  changed,  and  it  is  better  to  run  the  risk  of  a 
mistake  than  to  put  down  anything  that  does 
not  convey  a  distinct  idea  to  the  reader's  mind. 
It  is  of  course  far  more  agreeable  to  paraphrase 
than  to  translate,  and  as  the  Kritik  is  accessible 
in  English,  this  course  was  adopted  in  the  former 
volume ;  but  it  is  due  to  Kant  to  put  his  Pro 
legomena  in  all  their  homeliness  literally  before  the 
reader,  that  he  may  judge  of  the  accuracy  of  the 
various  commentators  and  critics  who  discuss  it. 

I  have  reprinted  in  the  Appendix  the  suppressed 
passages  of  Kant's  First  Edition  of  the  Kritik. 
The  text  of  the  Prolegomena  and  of  these  Appen 
dices  has  been  carefully  revised  by  Mr.  Bernard, 
and  many  improvements  made.  We  have  also 
given  in  brackets  the  paging  of  the  original  edition, 
for  the  sake  of  the  references  made  to  it  in  our  first 

Voluma  J.  P.  MAHAFFY. 

TRINITY  COLLEGE,  DUBLIN, 
June  6th,  1889. 


CONTENTS 


PREFACE 
CONTENTS 


PAGE 
V 


INTRODUCTION i 

PREAMBLE    ON    THE    PECULIARITIES    OF    ALL    METAPHYSICAL 
COGNITION 

Of  the  Sources  of  Metaphysic  .          .          .          .          .          .13 

Concerning  the  kind  of  Cognition  which  can  alone  be  called 

Metaphysical  .          .          .          .          .          .          .          .          .14 

Observations    on    the    General    Division    of    Judgments    into 

Analytical  and  Synthetical    .         .          .          .          .          .        19 

The  General  Question  of  the  Prolegomena. — Is  Metaphysic  at  all 

possible  ?  *         t  .         .         .          .          .20 

The  General  Problem  :    How  is  Cognition  from  Pure  -Reason 

possible  ?  .         .         ;  .          .         .          .26 

How  are  Synthetic  Propositions  a  priori  possible  ?  .          .          .        27 

FIRST    PART    OF    THE   GENERAL    TRANSCENDENTAL    PROBLEM 
How  is  Pure  Mathematic  possible  ?         .          .          .          .          .          32* 


SECOND    PART  OF  THE  GENERAL   TRANSCENDENTAL   PROBLEM 


How  is  the  Pure  Science  of  Nature  [Physic]  possible 
Logical  Table  of  Judgments    . 


49 
59 


CONTENTS 


PAGE 

Transcendental  Table  of  the  Pure  Concepts  of  the  Under 
standing  .........  60 

Pure  Physiological  Table  of  the  Universal  Principles  of  the 

Science  of  Nature  ........  60 

How  is  Nature  itself  possible  ?         .          .          .         .         .         .77 

APPENDIX   TO   THE   PURE   SCIENCE   OF   NATURE 
Of  the  System  of  the  Categories      .          .         .         .          .          .83 

THIRD   PART   OF   THE   MAIN   TRANSCENDENTAL    PROBLEM 

How  is  Metaphysic  in  General  possible  ?  ....       89 

Prefatory  Remark  to  the  Dialectic  of  Pure  Reason  95 

The  Psychological  Idea  .......        96 

The  Cosmological  Idea  .....  .102 

Table  of  Dialectical  Assertions  of  Pure  Reason          .  .103 

The  Theological  Idea    .          .          .          .          .  .          .114 

General  Remark  on  the  Transcendental  Ideas  .  .115 

CONCLUSION. — On  the  Bounds  of  Pure  Reason        .  .116 

SOLUTION  OF  THE  GENERAL  QUESTION  OF  THE  PROLEGOMENA 

How  is  Metaphysic  possible  as  a  Science  ?          .          .          .  135 

APPENDIX. — On  what  can  be  done  to  make  Metaphysic  actual  as 

a  Science       .........      143 

SPECIMEN    OF    A   JUDGMENT    ON    THE    KRITIK   PRIOR    TO 

ITS    EXAMINATION 145 

APPENDIX    A 

ON  THE  DEDUCTION  OF  THE  PURE  CONCEPTS  OF  THE 
UNDERSTANDING 

Of  the  a  priori  Grounds  of  the  Possibility  of  Experience   .  155 

Of  the  Relation  of  the  Understanding  to  Objects  in  General,  and 

of  the  Possibility  of  Cognising  them  a  priori      .          .          .      1 70 
Summary  Statement  of  the  Correctness  and  Possibility  of  this 
and    no    other    Deduction    of  the    Pure   Concepts   of  the 
Understanding         .         .         .          .         ,         .         .  180 


CONTENTS  xi 


APPENDIX    B 

p  PAGE 

^DISTINCTION    BETWEEN    NOUMENA    AND    PHENOMENA    .       1 82 


APPENDIX   C 

THE    FIRST    PARALOGISM,    OF    SUBSTANTIALITY 

Kritik  of  the  First  Paralogism  of  Pure  Psychology     .          .          .189 
The  Second  Paralogism,  of  Simplicity      .          .          .          .          .191 

Kritik  of  the  Second  Paralogism  of  Transcendental  Psychology     191 
Third  Paralogism,  of  Personality     .          .          .          .          .          .199 

Kritik  of  the  Third  Paralogism  of  Transcendental  Psychology  .  199 
The  Fourth  Paralogism,  of  Ideality  (of  External  Relations)  .  203 
Kritik  of  the  Fourth  Paralogism  of  Transcendental  Psychology  203 
'Reflection  concerning  the  whole  of  Pure  Psychology,  as  an 

Appendix  to  these  Paralogisms         .          .          .          .          .214 


APPENDIX    D 

PART    OF     THE     9TH     SECTION    OF    THE    ANTINOMY  OF    THE 
PURE    REASON 

Possibility  of  Causality  through  Freedom  in  Harmony  with  the 

Universal  Law  of  Natural  Necessity  .  .  .  .232 

Further  Elucidation  of  the  Cosmological  Idea  of  Freedom  in 

Harmony  with  the  Universal  Law  of  Natural  Necessity  .  235 


KANT'S 

PROLEGOMENA   TO    ANY   FUTURE 
METAPHYSIC 

INTRODUCTION 

THESE  Prolegomena  are  for  the  use,  not  of  pupils,  but  of 
future  teachers,  and  are  intended  to  serve  even  the  latter, 
not  in  arranging  their  exposition  of  an  existing  science,  but 
in  discovering  this  science  itself. 

There  are  learned  men,  to  whom  the  history  of  philo 
sophy  (both  ancient  and  modern)  is  philosophy  itself;  for 
such  the  present  Prolegomena  are  not  written.  They  must 
wait  till  those  who  endeavour  to  draw  from  the  fountain  of 
reason  itself  have  made  out  their  case ;  it  will  then  be  the 
historian's  turn  to  inform  the  world  of  what  has  been  done. 
Moreover,  nothing  can  be  said,  which  in  their  opinion  has 
not  been  said  already,  and  indeed  this  may  be  applied  as 
an  infallible  prediction  to  all  futurity;  for  as  the  human 
reason  has  for  many  centuries  pursued  with  ardour  infinitely 
various  [2]  objects  in  various  ways,  it  is  hardly  to  be 
expected  that  we  should  not  be  able  to  match  every  new 
thing  with  some  old  thing  not  unlike  it. 

My  object  is  to  persuade  all  who  think    Metaphysic 

II  B 


2  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [2-3 

worth  studying,  that  it  is  absolutely  necessary  to  adjourn 
for  the  present  this  (historical)  labour,  to  consider  all  that 
has  been  done  as  undone,  and  to  start  first  of  all  with  the 
question,  'Whether  such  a  thing  as  metaphysic  be  at  all 
possible?' 

If  it  be  a  science,  how  comes  it  that  it  cannot,  like  other 
sciences,  obtain  for  itself  an  universal  and  permanent 
recognition?  If  not,  how  is  it  ever  making  constant 
pretensions,  under  this  supposition,  and  keeping  the  human 
mind  in  suspense  with  hopes  that  never  fade,  and  yet  are 
never  fulfilled  ?  Whether  then,  as  a  result,  we  demonstrate 
our  knowledge  or  our  ignorance,  we  must  come  once  for  all 
to  a  definite  conclusion  about  the  nature  of  this  pretended 
science,  which  cannot  possibly  remain  on  its  present  footing. 
It  seems  almost  ridiculous,  while  every  other  science  is 
continually  advancing,  that  in  this,  which  would  be  very 
Wisdom,  at  whose  oracle  all  men  inquire,  we  should  per 
petually  revolve  round  the  same  point,  without  gaining  a 
single  step.  And  so  its  followers  having  melted  away,  we 
do  not  find  men  who  feel  able  to  shine  in  other  sciences 
venturing  their  reputation  here,  where  everybody,  however 
ignorant  in  other  matters,  pretends  to  deliver  a  final  verdict, 
as  in  this  domain  [3]  there  is  as  yet  no  certain  weight  and 
measure  to  distinguish  sound  knowledge  from  shallow  talk. 

But  after  long  elaboration  of  a  science,  when  men  begin 
to  wonder  how  far  it  has  advanced,  it  is  not  without  pre 
cedent  that  the  question  should  at  last  occur,  whether  and 
how  such  a  science  be  even  possible?  For  the  human 
reason  is  so  constructive,  that  it  has  already  several  times 
built  up  a  tower,  and  then  razed  it  to  examine  the  nature 
of  the  foundation.  It  is  never  too  late  to  mend ;  but  if  the 
change  comes  late,  there  is  always  more  difficulty  in  setting 
it  going. 


3-4]  INTRODUCTION 


The  question  whether  a  science  be  possible,  presupposes 
a  doubt  as  to  its  actuality.  But  such  a  doubt  offends  the 
men  whose  whole  possessions  consist  of  this  supposed 
jewel;  hence  he  who  raises  the  doubt  must  expect  op 
position  from  all  sides.  Some,  in  the  proud  consciousness 
of  their  possessions,  which  are  ancient,  and  therefore  con 
sidered  legitimate,  will  take  their  metaphysical  compendia 
in  their  hands,  and  look  down  on  him  with  contempt ; 
others,  who  never  see  anything  except  it  be  identical  with 
what  they  have  seen  before,  will  not  understand  him,  and 
everything  will  remain  for  a  time,  as  if  nothing  had  happened 
to  excite  the  concern,  or  the  hope,  for  an  impending 
change. 

Nevertheless,  I  venture  to  predict  that  the  independent 
reader  of  these  Prolegomena  will  not  only  doubt  his  previous 
science,  but  ultimately  be  [4]  fully  persuaded,  that  it  cannot 
exist  without  satisfying  the  demands  here  stated,  on  which 
its  possibility  depends ;  and,  as  this  has  never  been  done, 
that  there  is,  as  yet,  no  such  thing  as  Metaphysic.  But  as 
it  can  never  cease  to  be  in  demand — 

1  Rusticus  expectat,  dum  defluat  amnis,  at  ille 
Labitur  et  labetur  in  omne  volubilis  aevum  ; ' — 

since  the  interests  of  mankind  are  interwoven  with  it  so 
intimately,  he  must  confess  that  a  radical  reform,  or  rather 
a  new  birth  of  the  science  after  an  original  plan,  must  be 
unavoidably  at  hand,  however  men  may  struggle  against  it 
for  a  while. 

Since  the  Essays  of  Locke  and  Leibnitz,  or  rather  since 
the  origin  of  metaphysic  so  far  as  we  know  its  history, 
nothing  has  ever  happened  which  might  have  been  more 
decisive  to  the  fortunes  of  the  science  than  the  attack  made 
upon  it  by  David  Hume.  He  threw  no  light  on  this 


4  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [4-5 

species  of  knowledge,  but  he  certainly  struck  a  spark  from 
which  light  might  have  been  obtained,  had  it  caught  a 
proper  substance  to  nurture  and  develop  the  flame. 

Hume  started  chiefly  from  a  single  but  important  con 
cept  in  Metaphysic — that  of  Cause  and  Effect  (including 
the  deduced  notions  of  action  and  power).  He  calls  on 
reason,  which  pretends  to  have  generated  this  notion  from 
itself,  to  answer  him  with  what  right  it  thinks  anything  to 
be  so  constituted,  that  if  granted,  something  else  must 
necessarily  be  [5]  granted  thereby ;  for  this  is  the  meaning 
of  the  concept  of  cause.  He  demonstrated  irresistibly  that 
it  was  perfectly  impossible  for  reason  to  think  such  a  com 
bination  by  means  of  concepts  and  a  priori — a  combination 
that  contains  necessity.  We  cannot  at  all  see  why,  in 
consequence  of  the  existence  of  one  thing,  another  must 
necessarily  exist,  or  how  the  concept  of  such  a  combination 
can  arise  a  priori.  Hence  he  inferred,  that  reason  was 
altogether  deluded  by  this  concept,  which  it  considered 
erroneously  as  one  of  its  children,  whereas  in  reality  the 
concept  was  nothing  but  the  bastard  offspring  of  the 
imagination,  impregnated  by  experience,  and  so  bringing 
certain  representations  under  the  Law  of  Association.  The 
subjective  necessity,  that  is,  the  custom  which  so  arises,  is 
then  substituted  for  an  objective  necessity  from  real  know 
ledge.1  Hence  he  inferred  that  the  reason  had  no  power 
to  think  such  combinations,  even  generally,  because  its 
concepts  would  then  be  mere  inventions,  and  all  its  pre 
tended  a  priori  cognitions  nothing  but  common  experiences 
marked  with  a  false  stamp.  In  plain  language  there  is  not, 
and  cannot  be,  any  such  thing  as  metaphysic  at  all.2  This 

1  Lit.  insight.     M. 

2  Nevertheless  Hume  called  this  very  destructive  science  metaphysic, 
and  attached  to  it  great  value.     '  Metaphysic  and  morals  (he  says  in  the 


6-7J  INTRODUCTION 


conclusion,  however  [6]  hasty  and  mistaken,  was  at  least 
founded  upon  investigation,  and  the  investigation  deserved 
to  have  suggested  to  the  brighter  spirits  of  his  day  a  com 
bined  attempt  at  a  happy  solution  of  the  problem  proposed 
by  him,  if  such  solution  were  possible.  Thus  a  complete 
reform  of  the  science  must  have  resulted. 

But  the  perpetual  hard  fate  of  metaphysic  would  not  allow 
him  to  be  understood.  We  cannot  without  a  certain  sense 
of  pain  consider  how  utterly  his  opponents,  Reid,  Oswald, 
Beattie,  and  even  Priestley,  missed  the  point  of  the  problem. 
For  while  they  were  ever  assuming  as  conceded  what  he 
doubted,  and  demonstrating  with  eagerness  and  often  with 
arrogance  what  he  never  thought  of  disputing,  they  so 
overlooked  his  indication  towards  a  better  state  of  things, 
that  everything  remained  undisturbed  in  its  old  condition. 

The  question  was  not  whether  the  concept  of  cause  was 
right,  useful,  and  even  indispensable  with  regard  to  our 
knowledge  of  nature,  for  this  Hume  [7]  had  never  doubted. 
But  the  question  to  which  Hume  expected  an  answer  was 
this,  whether  that  concept  could  be  thought  by  the  reason 
a  priori,  and  whether  it  consequently  possessed  an  inner 
truth,  independent  of  all  experience,  and  therefore  applied 
more  widely  than  to  the  mere  objects  of  experience.  It 
was  surely  a  question  concerning  the  origin^  not  concerning 
the  indispensable  use  of  the  concept.  Had  the  former 
question  been  determined,  the  conditions  of  the  use  and 

4th  part  of  his  Essays)  are  the  most  important  branches  of  science ; 
mathematics  and  physics  are  not  worth  half  so  much.'  But  the  acute 
author  was  here  merely  regarding  the  negative  use  arising  from  the 
moderation  of  the  extravagant  pretensions  of  speculative  reason,  and 
the  complete  settlement  of  the  many  endless  and  troublesome  contro 
versies  that  mislead  mankind.  He  overlooked  the  positive  injury  which 
results,  if  the  reason  be  deprived  of  its  most  important  prospects,  which 
can  alone  supply  to  the  will  the  highest  aim  of  all  its  efforts. 


6  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [7-8 

valid  application  of  the  concept  would  have  been  given 
ip so  facto. 

But  the  opponents  of  the  great  thinker  should  have 
probed  very  deeply  into  the  nature  of  the  reason,  so  far  as 
it  concerns  pure  thinking,  if  they  would  satisfy  the  conditions 
of  the  problem — a  task  which  did  not  suit  them.  They 
therefore  discovered  a  more  convenient  means  of  putting  on 
a  bold  face  without  any  proper  insight  into  the  question,  by 
appealing  to  the  common  sense  of  mankind.  It  is  indeed  a 
great  gift  of  God,  to  possess  right,  or  (as  they  now  call  it) 
plain  common  sense.  But  this  common  sense  must  be 
shown  practically,  by  well-considered  and  reasonable 
thoughts  and  words,  not  by  appealing  to  it  as  an  oracle, 
when  you  can  advance  nothing  rational  in  justification  of 
yourself.  To  appeal  to  common  sense,  when  insight  and 
science  fail,  and  no  sooner — this  is  one  of  the  subtile 
discoveries  of  modern  times,  by  means  of  which  the  most 
vapid  babbler  can  safely  enter  the  lists  with  the  most 
thorough-  [8]  going  thinker,  and  hold  his  own.  But  as  long 
as  a  particle  of  insight  remains,  no  one  would  think  of 
having  recourse  to  this  subterfuge.  For  what  is  it,  but  an 
appeal  to  the  opinion  of  the  multitude,  of  whose  applause 
the  philosopher  is  ashamed,  while  the  popular  and  super 
ficial  man  glories  and  confides  in  it?  I  should  think 
Hume  might  fairly  have  laid  as  much  claim  to  sound  sense 
as  Beattie,  and  besides  to  a  critical  understanding  (such  as 
the  latter  did  not  possess),  which  keeps  common  sense 
within  such  limits  as  to  prevent  it  from  speculating,  or,  if 
it  does  speculate,  keeps  it  from  wishing  to  decide  when  it 
cannot  satisfy  itself  concerning  its  own  principles.  By  this 
means  alone  can  common  sense  remain  sound  sense. 
Chisels  and  hammers  may  suffice  to  work  a  piece  of  wood, 
but  for  steel-engraving  we  require  a  special  instrument. 


8-9]  INTRODUCTION 


Thus  common  sense  and  speculative  understanding  are 
each  serviceable  in  their  own  way,  the  former  in  judgments 
which  apply  immediately  to  experience,  the  latter  when  we 
judge  universally  from  mere  concepts,  as  in  metaphysic, 
where  that  which  calls  itself  (often  per  antiphrasiri)  sound 
common  sense  has  no  right  to  judge  at  all. 

I  honestly  confess,  the  suggestion  of  David  Hume  was 
the  very  thing,  which  many  years  ago  first  interrupted  my 
dogmatic  slumber,  and  gave  my  investigations  in  the  field 
of  speculative  philosophy  quite  a  new  direction.  I  was  far 
from  following  him  [9]  in  all  his  conclusions,  which  only 
resulted  from  his  regarding  not  the  whole  of  his  problem, 
but  a  part,  which  by  itself  can  give  us  no  information.  If 
we  start  from  a  well-founded,  but  undeveloped,  thought, 
which  another  has  bequeathed  to  us,  we  may  well  hope  by 
continued  reflection  to  advance  farther  than  the  acute  man, 
to  whom  we  owe  the  first  spark  of  light. 

I  therefore  first  tried  whether  Hume's  objection  could 
not  be  put  into  a  general  form,  and  soon  found  that  the 
concept  of  the  connexion  of  cause  and  effect  was  by  no 
means  the  only  one  by  which  the  understanding  thinks  the 
connexion  of  things  a  priori,  but  rather  that  metaphysic 
consists  altogether  of  such  connexions.  I  sought  to  make 
certain  of  their  number,  and  when  I  had  succeeded  in  this 
to  my  expectation,  by  starting  from  a  single  principle,  I 
proceeded  to  the  deduction  of  these  concepts,  which  I  was 
now  certain  were  not  deduced  from  experience,  as  Hume 
had  apprehended,  but  sprang  from  the  pure  understanding. 
This  deduction,  which  seemed  impossible  to  my  acute 
predecessor,  which  had  never  even  occurred  to  any  one 
else,  though  they  were  all  using  the  concepts  unsuspiciously 
without  questioning  the  basis  of  their  objective  validity — 
this  deduction  was  the  most  difficult  task  ever  undertaken 


8  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [9-11 

in  aid  of  metaphysic.  More  especially,  no  existing  meta- 
physic  could  assist  me  in  the  least,  because  this  deduction 
must  prove  the  [10]  very  possibility  of  metaphysic.  But  as 
soon  as  I  had  succeeded  in  solving  Hume's  problem  not 
merely  in  a  particular  case,  but  with  respect  to  the  whole 
faculty  of  pure  reason,  I  could  proceed  safely,  though 
slowly,  to  determine  the  whole  sphere  of  pure  reason 
completely  and  from  general  principles,  in  its  bounds,  as  well 
as  in  its  contents.  This  was  what  metaphysic  required,  in 
order  to  construct  its  system  safely. 

But  I  fear  that  the  carrying  out  of  Hume's  problem  in  its 
widest  extent  (viz.  my  Kritik  of  the  Pure  Reason)  will  fare 
as  the  problem  itself  fared,  when  first  proposed.  It  will  be 
misjudged  because  it  is  misunderstood,  and  misunderstood 
because  men  choose  to  skim  through  the  book,  and  not  to 
think  through  it — a  disagreeable  task,  because  the  work  is 
dry,  obscure,  opposed  to  all  ordinary  notions,  and  moreover 
voluminous.  I  confess,  however,  I  did  not  expect  to  hear 
from  philosophers  complaints  of  want  of  popularity,  enter 
tainment,  and  facility,  when  the  existence  of  a  highly 
esteemed  and  to  us  indispensable  cognition  is  at  stake, 
which  cannot  be  established  otherwise  than  by  the  strictest 
rules  of  scholastic  accuracy.  Popularity  may  follow,  but  is 
inadmissible  at  the  commencement.  Yet  as  regards  a  certain 
obscurity,  arising  partly  from  the  extent  of  the  plan,  in 
which  the  principal  points  of  the  investigation  cannot  be 
easily  gathered  into  view,  the  complaint  is  partly  just,  and 
I  intend  to  remove  it  by  the  present  Prolegomena. 

[u]  The  work  which  represents  the  pure  faculty  of 
reason  in  its  whole  compass  and  bounds  will  always  remain 
the  groundwork  to  which  the  Prolegomena,  as  a  pre 
liminary  exercise,  refer  •  for  we  must  have  that  Kritik 
completed  as  a  science,  systematically,  in  its  minutest 


n-12]  INTRODUCTION 


details,  before  we  can  think  of  letting  Metaphysic  appear  on 
the  scene,  or  even  have  the  most  distant  hope  of  attaining  it. 

We  have  been  long  accustomed  to  seeing  antiquated 
knowledge  produced  as  new  by  being  taken  out  of  its 
former  context,  and  fitted  into  a  suit  of  any  fancy  pattern 
under  new  titles.  Most  readers  will  set  out  by  expecting 
nothing  else  from  the  Kritik ;  but  these  Prolegomena  may 
persuade  him  that  it  is  a  perfectly  new  science,  of  which  no 
one  has  ever  even  thought,  the  very  idea  of  which  was 
unknown,  and  for  which  nothing  hitherto  accomplished  can 
be  of  the  smallest  use,  except  it  be  the  indication  suggested 
by  Hume's  doubts.  Yet  even  he  did  not  suspect  such 
a  formal  science,  but  ran  his  ship  ashore,  for  safety's  sake, 
on  scepticism,  there  to  let  it  lie  and  rot ;  whereas  my  object 
is  rather  to  give  it  a  pilot,  who,  by  means  of  safe  astro 
nomical  principles  drawn  from  a  knowledge  of  the  globe, 
and  provided  with  a  complete  chart  and  compass,  may  steer 
the  ship  safely,  whither  he  listeth. 

If  we  proceed  to  a  perfectly  isolated  and  peculiar  new 
science,  with  the  presupposition  that  we  can  judge  it  by 
means  of  a  supposed  science  that  has  [12]  been  already 
acquired,  whereas  the  reality  of  this  latter  must  be  first  of  all 
thoroughly  questioned — if  we  do  this,  it  will  make  men 
think  they  merely  recognise  old  knowledge.  For  the  terms 
are  similar,  with  this  difference,  that  everything  must  appear 
distorted,  absurd,  and  unintelligible,  because  men  start  from 
a  mental  attitude  not  the  author's,  but  their  own,  which 
through  long  habit  has  become  a  second  nature.  But  the 
voluminous  character  of  the  work,  so  far  as  it  depends  on 
the  subject,  and  not  the  exposition,  its  consequent  un 
avoidable  dryness,  and  its  scholastic  accuracy — these  are 
qualities  which  can  only  benefit  the  science,  though  they 
may  damage  the  book. 


io  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [12-13 

Few  writers  are  gifted  with  the  subtilty,  and  at  the  same 
time  with  the  grace  of  David  Hume,  or  with  the  depth,  as 
well  as  the  elegance,  of  Moses  Mendelssohn.  Yet  I  flatter 
myself  I  might  have  made  my  own  exposition  popular,  had 
my  object  been  merely  to  sketch  out  a  plan,  and  leave  its 
completion  to  others,  instead  of  having  my  heart  in  the 
welfare  of  the  science  that  I  had  so  long  pursued  ;J  in  truth, 
it  required  no  little  constancy,  and  even  self-denial,  to 
postpone  the  sweets  of  an  immediate  [13]  success  to  the 
prospect  of  a  slower,  but  more  lasting  reputation. 

Making  plans  is  often  the  occupation  of  a  luxurious  and 
boastful  mind,  which  thus  obtains  the  reputation  of  a 
creative  genius,  by  demanding  what  it  cannot  itself  supply ; 
by  censuring,  what  it  cannot  improve ;  and  by  proposing, 
what  it  knows  not  where  to  find.  And  yet  something 
more  should  belong  to  a  sound  plan  of  a  general  Kritik  of 
the  Pure  Reason  than  mere  conjectures,  if  this  plan  is  to 
be  other  than  the  usual  declamation  of  pious  aspirations. 
But  pure  reason  is  a  sphere  so  separate  and  self-contained, 
that  we  cannot  touch  a  part  without  affecting  all  the  rest. 
We  can  therefore  do  nothing  without  first  determining  the 
position  of  each  part,  and  its  relation  to  the  rest ;  for,  as 
our  judgment  cannot  be  corrected  by  anything  without, 
the  validity  and  use  of  every  part  depends  upon  the  relation 
in  which  it  stands  to  all  the  rest  within  the  reason. 

So  in  the  structure  of  an  organized  body,  the  end  of 
each  member  can  only  be  deduced  from  the  full  conception 
of  the  whole.  It  may,  then,  be  said  of  such  a  Kritik,  that 

\  1  It  is  not  a  little  remarkable  that  Kant  expresses  an  exactly  contrary 
opinion  in  the  conclusion  to  his  Second  Preface  to  the  Kritik,  where  he 
invites  those  who  are  possessed  of  the  gift  of  popular  teaching  to  assist 
in  explaining  his  system,  and  where  he  confesses  himself  devoid  of  it.  — 
Kritik)  p.  xlii.  M. 


13-15]  INTRODUCTION  n 

it  is  never  trustworthy  except  it  be  perfectly  complete,  down 
to  the  smallest  elements  of  the  reason.  In  the  sphere  of 
this  faculty  you  can  determine  either  everything  or  nothing. 
But  although  a  mere  sketch,  preceding  the  Kritik  of  Pure 
Reason,  would  be  unintelligible,  unreliable  and  useless,  it 
is  all  the  more  useful  as  a  [14]  sequel.  For  so  we  are  able 
to  grasp  the  whole,  to  examine  in  detail  the  chief  points  of 
importance  in  the  science,  and  to  improve  in  many  respects 
our  exposition,  as  compared  with  the  first  execution  of  the 
work. 

-Such  is  the  plan  sketched  out  in  the  following  pages, 
which,  after  the  completion  of  the  work,  may  be  carried  out 
analytically r,  though  the  work  itself  must  absolutely  be  exe 
cuted  in  the  synthetical  method,  in  order  that  the  science  may 
present  all  its  articulations,  as  the  structure  of  a  peculiar  cog 
nitive  faculty,  in  their  natural  combination.  But  should  any 
reader  find  this  plan,  which  I  publish  as  the  Prolegomena 
to  any  future  Metaphysic,  itself  difficult,  let  him  consider 
that  every  one  is  not  bound  to  study  Metaphysic,  that  there 
are  many  minds  which  succeed  very  well,  in  genuine  and 
even  deep  sciences  more  closely  allied  to  intuition,  while 
they  cannot  succeed  in  investigations  proceeding  only  by 
means  of  abstract  concepts.1  In  such  cases  men  should 
apply  their  talents  to  other  subjects.  But  he  that  under 
takes  to  judge,  or  still  more  to  construct  a  system  of  Meta 
physic,  [15]  must  satisfy  the  demands  here  made,  either  by 
adopting  my  solution,  or  by  thoroughly  refuting  it,  and 
substituting  another.  To  evade  it  is  impossible. 

1  It  is  nevertheless  to  be  observed  that  a  large  proportion  of  great 
metaphysicians  have  been  trained  and  distinguished  mathematicians. 
The  examples  of  Plato,  Aristotle,  Descartes,  Leibnitz,  Berkeley,  and 
Kant  will  occur  to  the  reader.  Even  in  the  present  day  there  are  some 
remarkable  cases  of  this  combination.  M. 


12  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [15 

In  conclusion,  let  it  be  remembered  that  this  much- 
abused  obscurity — a  very  common  cloak  for  men's  own 
laziness  or  stupidity — has  its  uses,  since  all  who  in  other 
sciences  observe  a  prudent  silence,  in  this  speak  authori 
tatively,  and  decide  boldly,  because  their  ignorance  is  not 
here  contrasted  with  the  knowledge  of  others.  Yet  it 
does  contrast  with  sound  critical  principles,  which  we  may 
therefore  commend  in  the  words  of  Virgil  : 

Ignavum,  fucos,  pecus  a  prsesepibus  arcent. 


[16]  PROLEGOMENA 

PREAMBLE    ON    THE    PECULIARITIES    OF    ALL 
METAPHYSICAL    COGNITION 

§   i.   Of  the  Sources  of  Metaphysic 

IF  we  wish  to  present  a  cognition  as  a  science ',  we  must 
first  determine  accurately  the  features  which  no  other 
science  has  in  common  with  it — in  fact  its  peculiarity, 
otherwise  the  boundaries  of  all  sciences  become  confused, 
and  none  of  them  can  be  treated  thoroughly  according  to 
its  nature. 

This  peculiarity  may  consist  of  a  simple  difference  of 
object,  or  of  the  sources  of  cognition,  or  of  the  kind  of 
cognition,  or  perhaps  of  all  three  conjointly.  On  this,  there 
fore,  depends  the  idea  of  a  possible  science  and  its  territory. 

First,  as  concerns  the  sources  of  metaphysical  cognition, 
its  very  concept  implies  that  they  cannot  be  empirical.  Its 
principles  (including  not  only  its  fundamental  judgments, 
but  its  fundamental  concepts)  must  never  be  derived  from 
experience.  It  must  not  be  physical  but  metaphysical 
knowledge,  viz.  knowledge  lying  beyond  experience.  It 
[17]  can  therefore  have  for  its  basis  neither  external  ex 
perience,  which  is  the  source  of  physics  proper,  nor  internal, 
which  is  the  basis  of  empirical  psychology.  It  is  there- 


i4  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [17-18 

fore  a  priori  knowledge,  coming  from  pure  Understanding 
and  pure  Reason. 

But  so  far  Metaphysic  would  not  be  distinguishable  from 
pure  Mathematic ;  it  must  therefore  be  called  pure  philosophi 
cal  cognition  ;  and  for  the  meaning  of  this  term  I  refer  to  the 
Kritikofthe  Pure  Reason,  p.  4  3  5,  where  the  distinction  between 
these  two  employments  of  the  reason  is  sufficiently  explained. 
So  far  concerning  the  sources  of  metaphysical  cognition. 

§  2.  Concerning  the  Kind  of  Cognition  which  can  alone  be 
called  Metaphysical. 

a. — Of  the  Distinction  between  Analytical  and  Synthetical 
Judgments  in  general.  The  peculiarity  of  its  sources  demands 
that  metaphysical  cognition  must  consist  of  nothing  but  a 
priori  judgments.  But  whatever  be  their  origin,  or  their 
logical  form,  there  is  a  distinction  in  judgments,  as  to  their 
content,  according  to  which  they  are  either  merely  explicative, 
adding  nothing  to  the  content  of  the  cognition,  or  ampliative, 
increasing  the  given  cognition :  the  former  may  be  called 
analytical,  the  latter  synthetical,  judgments. 

Analytical  judgments  express  nothing  in  the  predicate 
but  what  has  been  already  actually  thought  in  [18]  the  con 
cept  of  the  subject,  though  not  so  distinctly  or  with  the 
same  (full)  consciousness.1  When  I  say :  All  bodies  are 
extended,  I  have  not  amplified  in  the  least  my  concept  of 
body,  but  have  only  analysed  it,  as  extension  was  really 
thought  to  belong  to  that  concept  before  the  judgment  was 

1  The  difference  between  an  attribute  obscurely  felt  to  be  in  the  sub 
ject,  and  which  requires  a  judgment  to  explicate  it,  and  an  attribute 
necessarily  joined  to  the  subject,  seems  very  small  indeed.  But  a  little 
reflection  will  show  us  that  we  cannot  think  the  subject  without  the 
first,  whereas  the  second  is  always  seen  to  be  an  addition,  even  if  neces 
sary.  M. 


18-19]  PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION    15 

made,  though  it  was  not  expressed ;  this  judgment  is  there 
fore  analytical.  On  the  contrary,  this  judgment,  All  bodies 
have  weight,  contains  in  its  predicate  something  not  actually 
thought  in  the  general  concept  of  body ;  it  amplifies  my 
knowledge  by  adding  something  to  my  concept,  and  must 
therefore  be  called  synthetical. 

b. — The  Common  Principle  of  all  Analytical  Judgments 
is  the  Law  of  Contradiction.  All  analytical  judgments  de 
pend  wholly  on  the  law  of  Contradiction,  and  are  in  their 
nature  a  priori  cognitions,  whether  the  concepts  that  supply 
them  with  matter  be  empirical  or  not.  For  the  predicate 
of  an  affirmative  analytical  judgment  is  already  contained  in 
the  concept  of  the  subject,  of  which  it  cannot  be  denied 
without  contradiction.  In  the  same  way  its  opposite  is 
necessarily  denied  of  the  subject  in  an  analytical,  but  nega 
tive,  judgment,  by  the  [19]  same  law1  of  contradiction. 
Such  is  the  nature  of  the  judgments  :  all  bodies  are  ex 
tended,  and  no  bodies  are  unextended. 

For  this  very  reason  all  analytical  judgments  are  a  priori 
even  when  the  concepts  are  empirical,  as,  for  example,  Gold 
is  a  yellow  metal ;  for  to  know  this  I  require  no  experience 
beyond  my  concept  of  gold  as  a  yellow  metal :  it  is,  in  fact, 
the  very  concept,  and  I  need  only  analyse  it,  without  looking 
beyond  it  elsewhere. 

c. — Synthetical  Judgments  require  a  different  Principle  from 
the  Law  of  Contradiction.  There  are  synthetical  a  posteriori 
judgments  of  empirical  origin;  but  there  are  also  others  which 
are  certain  a  priori,  and  which  spring  from  pure  Understand 
ing  and  Reason.  Yet  they  both  agree  in  this,  that  they  can 
not  possibly  spring  from  the  principle  of  analysis,  or  the  law 
of  contradiction,  alone ;  they  require  a  quite  different  prin 
ciple,  though,  from  whatever  they  may  be  deduced,  they 
must  be  subject  to  the  law  of  contradiction,  which  must  never 


16  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [19-21 

be  violated,  even   though  everything  cannot  be  deduced 
from  it.     I  shall  first  classify  synthetical  judgments. 

1.  Empirical  Judgments  are  always  synthetical.1     [20] 
For  it  would  be  absurd  to  base  an  analytical  judgment  on 
experience,  as  our  concept  suffices  for  the  purpose  without 
requiring  any  testimony  from  experience.     That  body  is  ex 
tended,  is  a  judgment  established  a  priori,   and  not  an 
empirical  judgment.     For  before  appealing  to  experience, 
we  already  have  all  the  conditions  of  the  judgment  in  the 
concept  (of  the  subject),  from  which  we  have  but  to  elicit 
the  predicate  according  to  the  law  of  contradiction,  and 
thereby  to  become  conscious  of  the  necessity  of  the  judgment, 
which  experience  could  not  even  teach  us. 

2.  Mathematical  Judgments  are    all    synthetical.     This 
fact  seems  hitherto  to  have  altogether  escaped  the  observa 
tion  of  those  who  have  analysed  the  human  reason  ;    it  even 
seems  directly  opposed  to  all  their  conjectures,  though  in- 
contestably  certain,  and  most  important  in  its  consequences. 
For  as  it  was  found  that  the  conclusions  of  mathematicians 
all  proceed  according  to  the  law  of  contradiction  (as  is  de 
manded  by  all  apodeictic  certainty),  men  [21]  persuaded 
themselves  that  the  axioms  (fundamental  principles)  were 
known  from  the  same  law.     This  was  a  great  mistake,  for 
a    synthetical   proposition    can    indeed   be   comprehended 

1  See  the  very  important  passage  in  the  First  Edition  of  the  Kritik, 
quoted  by  me  on  p.  12  of  Kuno  Fischer's  Commentary.  'In  all  syn 
thetical  judgments  I  must  have  something  else  (x)  besides  the  concept 
of  the  subject,  to  which  the  understanding  must  apply,  in  order  to  dis 
cover  a  predicate  not  contained  in  the  subject.  In  the  case  of  empirical 
judgments  this  x  is  the  complete  experience  of  the  subject,  and  my 
concept  indicates  that  complete  experience  by  means  of  a  part  of  it,  to 
which  I  can  add  other  facts  of  the  same  experience,  as  belonging  to  the 
first.'  It  follows  that  these  propositions,  though  synthetical  as  regards 
the  concept,  become  analytical  as  regards  our  experience  when  actually 
completed.  Cf.  vol  i.  p.  36,  note.  M. 


21-22]    PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION  17 

according  to  the  law  of  contradiction,  but  only  by  pre 
supposing  another  synthetical  proposition  from  which  it 
follows,  never  in  itself. 

First  of  all,  we  must  observe  that  all  proper  mathematical 
judgments  are  a  priori^  and  not  empirical,  because  they 
carry  with  them  necessity,  which  cannot  be  obtained  from 
experience.  But  if  this  be  not  conceded  to  me,  very  good  ; 
I  shall  confine  my  assertion  to  pure  Mathematic,  the  very 
notion  of  which  implies  that  it  contains  pure  a  priori  and 
not  empirical  cognitions. 

It  might  at  first  be  thought  that  the  proposition  7  +  5  =  12 
is  a  mere  analytical  judgment,  following  from  the  concept  of 
the  sum  of  seven  and  five,  according  to  the  law  of  contra 
diction.  But  on  closer  examination  it  appears  that  the  con 
cept  of  the  sum  of  7  +  5  contains  merely  their  union  in  a 
single  number,  without  its  being  at  all  thought  what  the  par 
ticular  number  is  that  unites  them.  The  concept  of  twelve 
is  by  no  means  thought  by  merely  thinking  of  the  combina 
tion  of  seven  and  five ;  and  analyse  this  possible  sum  as  we 
may,  we  shall  not  discover  twelve  in  the  concept.  We  must 
go  beyond  these  concepts,  by  calling  to  our  aid  the  intuition 
corresponding  to  one  of  them,  say  our  five  fingers,  or  five 
[22]  [visible]  points  (as  Segner  did  in  his  arithmetic),  and 
we  must  add  successively  the  units  of  the  five  given  in  the 
intuition  to  the  concept  of  seven.1  Hence  our  concept  is 

1  The  reader  will  observe  that  to  the  concept  of  7,  the  intuition  of  5  is 
gradually  added  ;  it  is  not  an  addition  of  two  intuitions.  In  the  case 
of  2  +  2  =  4,  this  latter  may  be  the  case,  but  most  probably  more 
than  5  cannot  be  grasped  in  a  single  visible  intuition.  Accordingly  7  is 
first  made  up  of  5  +  2,  and  then  the  resulting  concept  used  for  further 
processes.  The  system  adopted  in  Roman  figures  (which  is  indeed  almost 
universal)  illustrates  the  point  exactly.  Instead  of  writing  six  points 
or  strokes,  we  write  VI,  substituting  the  symbol  V,  perhaps  a  rude  repre 
sentation  of  an  open  hand,  for  the  intuition  IIIII.  M. 
II  C 


1 8  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [22-23 

really  amplified  by  the  proposition  7  +  5  =  12,  and  we  add 
to  the  first  a  second,  not  thought  in  it.  Arithmetical 
judgments  are  therefore  always  synthetical,  and  the  more 
plainly  according  as  we  take  larger  numbers ;  for  in  such 
cases  it  is  clear  that,  however  closely  we  analyse  our  concepts 
without  calling  intuition  to  our  aid,  we  can  never  find  the 
sum  by  such  mere  dissection. 

Just  as  little  is  any  principle  of  geometry  analytical. 
That  a  straight  line  is  the  shortest  between  two  points,  is  a 
synthetical  proposition.  For  my  concept  of  straight  contains 
nothing  of  quantity,  but  only  a  quality.  The  attribute  of 
shortness  is  therefore  altogether  additional,  and  not  obtain 
able  by  any  analysis  of  the  concept.  Intuition,  which  alone 
makes  the  synthesis  possible,  must  here  also  be  brought  in 
to  assist  us. 

[23]  Some  other  principles,  assumed  by  geometers,  are 
indeed  actually  analytical,  and  depend  on  the  law  of  contra 
diction  ;  but  they  only  serve,  as  identical  propositions,  in 
the  chain  of  method,  and  not  as l  principles,  ex.  gr.  a  =  a, 
the  whole  is  equal  to  itself,  or  a  +  b  >  a,  the  whole  is  greater 
than  its  part.  And  yet  even  these,  though  they  are 
recognised  as  valid  from  mere  concepts,  are  only  admitted 
in  mathematics,  because  they  can  be  represented  in  intui 
tion.2  What  usually  makes  us  believe  that  the  predicate 
of  such  apodeictic  judgments  is  already  contained  in  our 
concept,  and  that  the  judgment  is  therefore  analytical,  is 
the  ambiguity  of  the  expression.  For  we  ought  to  add  in 

1  Not  'from  principles  ; '  I  think  we  should  read  als,  not  aus.     M. 

2  The  remainder  of  this  paragraph  is  very  difficult,  except  we  under 
stand  it,  not  of  the  analytical  judgments  just  described,  and  to  which 
Kant's  language  would  seem  to  refer  it,  but  of  the  synthetical  axioms 
previously  discussed.     The  whole  passage,  beginning  from  the  analysis 
of  7  +  5  =  12,  is  transcribed  verbatim  into  the  Second  Edition  of  the 
Kritik,  without  a  single  explanation.     Cf.  vol.  i.  p.  38.     M. 


23-25!  PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION    19 

thought  a  certain  predicate  to  a  given  concept,  and  this 
necessity  already  attaches  to  the  concepts.  But  the  question 
is  not  what  we  must  join  in  thought  to  the  given  concept, 
but  what  we  actually  think  in  it,  though  obscurely ;  and  so 
it  appears  that  the  predicate  belongs  to  these  concepts 
necessarily  indeed,  yet  not  as  thought  in  [24]  the 
concept  itself,  but  through  the  intervention  of  an  intuition, 
which  must  be  added. 

§  3.      Observations  on   the  General  Division  of  Judgments 
into  Analytical  and  Synthetical. 

This  division  is  indispensable,  as  concerns  the  Kritik  of 
the  human  understanding,  and  therefore  deserves  to  be 
called  classical ;  I  know  not  whether  it  is  elsewhere  of 
important  use.  And  this  is  the  reason  why  dogmatic 
philosophers,  who  always  seek  the  sources  of  metaphysical 
judgments  in  Metaphysic  itself,  and  not  apart  from  it,  in  the 
pure  laws  of  reason  generally — why  these  men  altogether 
neglected  this  apparently  obvious  distinction.  So  it  was 
that  the  celebrated  Wolf,  and  his  acute  follower  Baum- 
garten,  came  to  seek  the  proof  of  the  principle  of  Sufficient 
Reason,  which  is  clearly  synthetical,  in  the  principle  of 
Contradiction.  In  Locke's  Essay,  on  the  contrary,  I  find 
an  indication  of  my  division.  For  in  the  fourth  book 
(chap.  iii.  §  9,  seq.\  after  he  has  discussed  the  various 
connexions  of  representations  in  judgments,  and  their 
sources,  one  of  which  he  makes  identity  and  contradiction 
(analytical  judgments),  and  another  the  coexistence  of 
representations  in  a  subject,  he  afterwards  confesses  (§  10) 
that  our  a  priori  knowledge  of  the  latter  is  very  narrow,  and 
almost  nothing.  But  in  his  remarks  on  this  species  of 
cognition,  there  is  so  [25]  little  of  what  is  definite,  and 


20  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [25-26 

reduced  to  rules,1  that  we  cannot  wonder  if  no  one,  not 
even  Hume,  was  led  to  make  investigations  concerning  this 
sort  of  judgments.  For  such  general  and  yet  determinate 
principles  are  not  easily  learned  from  other  men,  who  have 
had  them  obscurely  in  their  minds.  We  must  hit  on  them 
first  by  our  own  reflection,  then  we  find  them  elsewhere, 
where  we  could  not  possibly  have  found  them  at  first, 
because  the  authors  themselves  did  not  know  that  such  an 
idea  lay  at  the  basis  of  their  observations.  Men  who  never 
think  independently  have  nevertheless  the  acuteness  to 
discover  everything,  after  it  has  been  once  shown  them,  in 
what  was  said  long  since,  though  no  one  ever  saw  it  there 
before. 

[26]  §  4.      The  General  Question  of  the  Prolegomena. — Is 
Metaphysic  at  all  possible  ? 

Were  a  Metaphysic,  which  could  maintain  its  place  as 
a  science,  really  in  existence — if  we  could  say,  here  is 
Metaphysic,  learn  it,  and  it  will  convince  you  irresistibly  and 
irrevocably  of  its  truth — then  this  question  would  be  useless, 
and  there  would  only  remain  that  other,  which  is  rather  a 
test  of  our  acuteness,  than  a  proof  of  the  existence  of  the 

1  Unfortunately,  Kant  had  not  observed  the  really  decisive  passage 
in  Locke  on  the  point.  When  discussing  officially  the  various  kinds  of 
agreement  and  disagreement  among  our  ideas,  he  actually  enumerates 
the  very  classes,  with  the  very  examples,  of  Kant.  First,  judgments  of 
identity  and  diversity,  sc.  analytical,  and  his  example  is  :  Blue  is  not 
yellow.  Secondly,  judgments  of  relation,  an  ill-chosen  term,  but 
evidently  the  same  as  Kant's  synthetical  a  priori,  for  his  example  is  a 
mathematical  judgment,  such  as  :  The  angles  of  a  triangle  are  equal  to 
two  right  angles.  Thirdly,  judgments  of  coexistence  (synthetical  a 
posteriori},  such  as  :  Gold  is  fusible.  Fourthly,  judgments  of  existence 
(afterwards  distinguished  by  Kant  as  subjectively  synthetical),  such  as  : 
God  is.  Can  anything  be  more  distinct  than  this  ?  See  Locke's  Essay, 
book  iv.  chap.  i.  §  7,  and  cf.  vol.  i.  p.  33.  M. 


26-27]  PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION   21 

thing  itself — I  mean,  the  question  how  the  science  is  possible^ 
and  how  the  understanding  comes  to  attain  it.  But  the 
human  reason  has  not  been  so  fortunate  in  this  case.  There 
is  no  single  book  to  which  you  can  point  as  you  do  to 
Euclid,  and  say  :  This  is  Metaphysic  •  here  you  may  find  the 
noblest  objects  of  this  science,  the  knowledge  of  a  highest 
Being,  and  of  a  future  existence,  proved  from  principles  of 
pure  reason.  We  can  be  shown  indeed  many  judgments, 
demonstrably  certain,  and  never  questioned ;  but  these  are 
all  analytical,  and  rather  concern  the  materials  and  the 
scaffolding  for  Metaphysic,  than  the  extension  of  knowledge, 
which  is  our  proper  object  in  studying  it  (§  2).  Even 
supposing  you  produce  synthetical  judgments  (such  as  the 
law  of  Sufficient  Reason),  which  you  could  never  have 
proved,  as  you  ought,  from  pure  reason  a  priori,  but  which 
we  gladly  concede,  nevertheless,  when  they  come  to  be 
employed  for  your  principal  object,  you  lapse  [27]  into  such 
doubtful  assertions,  that  in  all  ages  one  Metaphysic  has 
contradicted  another,  either  in  its  assertions,  or  their  proofs, 
and  thus  has  itself  destroyed  its  own  claim  to  lasting  assent. 
Nay  the  very  attempts  to  set  up  such  a  science  are  the  main 
cause  of  the  early  appearance  of  scepticism,  a  mental 
attitude  in  which  reason  treats  itself  with  such  violence 
that  it  could  never  have  arisen  save  from  complete  despair 
of  ever  satisfying  our  most  important  aspirations.  For  long 
before  men  began  to  question  nature  methodically,  they 
questioned  isolated  reason,  which  had  to  some  extent  been 
exercised  by  means  of  ordinary  experience;  for  reason  is 
ever  present,  while  laws  of  nature  must  usually  be  sought 
with  labour.  So  Metaphysic  floated  to  the  surface,  like 
foam — like  it  also  in  this,  that  when  what  had  been  gathered 
was  dissolved,  there  immediately  appeared  a  new  supply  on 
the  surface,  to  be  ever  eagerly  collected  by  some,  while 


22  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSTC  [27-28 

others,  instead  of  seeking  in  the  depths  the  cause  of  the 
phenomenon,  thought  they  showed  their  wisdom  by  ridiculing 
the  idle  labour  of  their  neighbours. 

The  essential  and  distinguishing  feature  of  pure  mathe 
matical  cognition  among  all  other  a  priori  cognitions  is, 
that  it  cannot  at  all  proceed  from  concepts,  but  only  by 
means  of  the  construction  of  concepts  (Kritik,  p.  435).  As 
therefore  in  its  judgments  it  must  proceed  beyond  the 
concept  to  that  which  the  corresponding  intuition  con 
tains,  these  judg-[28]ments  neither  can,  nor  ought  to, 
arise  analytically,  by  dissecting  the  concept,  but  are 
all  synthetical. 

I  cannot  refrain  from  pointing  out  the  disadvantages 
resulting  to  philosophy  from  the  neglect  of  this  easy  and 
apparently  insignificant  observation.  Hume  indeed  was 
prompted  (a  task  worthy  of  a  philosopher)  to  cast  his  eye 
over  the  whole  field  of  a  priori  cognitions  in  which  the 
human  understanding  claims  such  mighty  possessions.  But 
he  incautiously  severed  from  it  a  whole,  and  indeed  its 
most  valuable,  province,  viz.  pure  mathematic.  For  he 
thought  its  nature,  or,  so  to  speak,  its  constitution,  depended 
on  totally  different  principles,  namely,  on  the  law  of  contra 
diction  alone ;  and  although  he  did  not  divide  judgments 
so  formally  or  universally  as  I  have  here  done,  what  he  said 
was  equivalent  to  this :  that  mathematic  contains  only 
analytical,  but  metaphysic  synthetical  a  priori  judgments. 
In  this  he  was  greatly  mistaken,  and  the  mistake  had  a 
decidedly  injurious  effect  upon  his  whole  conception 
[system].  But  for  this,  he  would  have  extended  his 
question  concerning  the  origin  of  our  synthetical  judgments 
far  beyond  the  metaphysical  concept  of  Causality,  and 
included  in  it  the  possibility  of  mathematic  a  priori  also,  for 
this  latter  he  must  have  assumed  to  be  equally  synthetical 


28-30]  PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION    23 

And  then  he  could  not  have  based  his  metaphysical 
judgments  on  mere  experience  without  subjecting  the 
axioms  of  mathematic  equally  to  experience,  a  thing  which 
[29]  he  was  far  too  acute  to  do.1  The  good  company 
into  which  metaphysic  would  thus  have  been  brought, 
would  have  saved  it  from  the  danger  of  a  contemptuous  ill- 
treatment,  for  the  thrust  intended  for  it  must  have  reached 
mathematic,  which  was  not  and  could  not  have  been  Hume's 
intention.  Thus  that  acute  man  would  have  been  led  into 
considerations  which  must  needs  be  similar  to  those  that 
now  occupy  us,  but  which  would  have  gained  inestimably 
by  his  inimitably  elegant  style. 

Proper  metaphysical  judgments  are  all  synthetical.  We 
must  distinguish  judgments  belonging  to  metaphysic  from 
properly  metaphysical  judgments.  Many  of  the  former  are 
analytical,  but  they  only  afford  the  means  for  metaphysical 
judgments,  which  are  the  whole  end  of  the  science,  and 
which  are  always  synthetical.  For  whatever  concepts  belong 
to  metaphysic  (as,  for  example,  substance),  the  judgments, 
which  arise  from  their  mere  analysis,  belong  also  to  meta 
physic;  as,  for  example,  substance  is  that  which  only  exists  as 
subject;  and  by  means  of  several  such  analytical  judgments, 
we  seek  to  approach  the  definition  of  the  concept.  But  as 
the  analysis  of  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding,  such  as 
are  found  in  [30]  metaphysic,  does  not  proceed  indifferently 
from  the  dissection  of  any  other  (empirical)  concept,  not 
belonging  to  metaphysic  (such  as  :  the  air  is  an  elastic 
fluid,  the  elasticity  of  which  is  not  removed  by  any  known 

1  Kant's  confidence  on  this  point  is  hardly  justified.  For  in  Hume's 
Essays  (which  he  declares  to  be  his  final  declaration  on  Philosophy) 
there  are  a  good  many  hints  that  mathematics  might  be  based  on 
experience.  Cf.  Essays,  vol.  ii.  p.  468,  note,  etc. ;  and  in  the  Treatise  it 
is  still  more  plain  that  he  regarded  experience  as  their  ultimate  ground. 
Cf.,  however,  vol.  i.  pp.  34  and  40,  note.  M. 


24  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  {30-31 

degree  of  cold),  it  follows  that  the  concept  indeed,  but  not 
the  analytical  judgment,  is  properly  metaphysical.  This 
science  has  something  peculiar  in  the  production  of  its 
a  priori  cognitions,  which  must  therefore  be  distinguished 
from  the  features  it  has  in  common  with  other  rational 
knowledge.  Thus  the  judgment,  "that  all  the  substance  in 
things  is  permanent,  is  a  synthetical  and  properly  meta 
physical  judgment. 

If  the  a  priori  principles,  which  constitute  the  materials 
of  metaphysic,  have  first  been  collected  on  fixed  principles, 
then  their  analysis  is  of  great  value ;  it  can  also  be  taught 
as  a  particular  part  (as  a  philosophia  definitiva),  containing 
nothing  but  analytical  judgments  pertaining  to  metaphysic, 
and  separate  from  the  synthetical,  which  constitute  meta 
physic  proper.  And  indeed  these  analyses  are  not  elsewhere 
of  much  value,  except  in  metaphysic,  that  is,  as  regards  the 
synthetical  judgments,  which  are  to  be  generated  by  these 
previously  analysed  concepts. 

The  conclusion  drawn  in  this  section  then  is,  that 
metaphysic  is  properly  concerned  with  synthetical  pro 
positions  a  priori^  and  these  alone  constitute  its  end,  for 
which  it  indeed  requires  various  analyses  [31]  of  its 
concepts,  which  are  analytical  judgments,  but  wherein  the 
procedure  is  not  different  from  that  in  every  other  sort  of 
knowledge,  in  which  we  merely  seek  to  render  our  concepts 
distinct  by  analysis.  But  the  generation  of  a  priori  cog 
nition,  as  well  of  intuition  as  according  to  concepts,  in  fine 
of  synthetical  propositions  a  priori  in  philosophical  cognition, 
this  makes  up  the  essential  matter  of  Metaphysic. 

Weary  therefore  as  well  of  dogmatism,  which  teaches  us 
nothing,  as  of  scepticism,  which  does  not  even  promise  us 
anything,  not  even  the  quiet  state  of  a  contented  ignorance — 
excited  [as  we  are]  by  the  importance  of  a  cognition  of 


31-32]  PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION  25 

which  we  stand  in  need,  and  rendered  suspicious  by  long 
experience  with  regard  to  all  knowledge  which  we  believe 
we  possess,  or  which  offers  itself,  under  the  title  of  pure 
reason — there  remains  but  one  critical  question  to  which  the 
answer  must  determine  our  future  procedure  :  Is  Metaphysic 
at  all  possible  1  But  this  question  must  be  answered  not 
by  sceptical  objections  to  the  assertions  of  actual  [systems 
of]  Metaphysic  (for  we  do  not  as  yet  admit  such  a  thing), 
but  from  the  conception,  as  yet  only  problematical ',  of  a 
science  of  this  sort. 

In  the  Kritik  of  the  Pure  Reason  I  have  treated  this 
question  synthetically,  by  making  inquiries  into  pure  reason 
itself,  and  endeavouring  in  this  source  to  determine  the 
elements  as  well  as  the  laws  of  its  pure  use  according  to 
principles.  The  task  is  diffi-[32]  cult,  and  requires  a 
resolute  reader  to  penetrate  by  degrees  into  a  system,  based 
on  no  data  except  the  reason  itself,  and  which  therefore 
seeks,  without  resting  upon  any  fact,  to  unfold  knowledge 
from  its  original  germs.  Prolegomena  on  the  contrary  are 
designed  for  exercises;  they  are  intended  rather  to  point 
out  what  we  have  to  do  in  order  to  realise  [if  possible]  a 
science,  than  to  propound  it.  They  must  therefore  rest 
upon  something  already  known  as  trustworthy,  from  which 
we  can  set  out  with  confidence,  and  ascend  to  sources  as 
yet  unknown,  the  discovery  of  which  will  not  only  explain 
to  us  what  we  knew,  but  exhibit  a  sphere  of  many  cognitions 
which  all  spring  from  the  same  sources.  The  method  of 
Prolegomena,  especially  of  those  designed  as  a  preparation 
for  future  metaphysic,  is  consequently  analytical. 

But  it  happens  fortunately,  that  though  we  cannot  assume 
metaphysic  to  be  an  actual  science,  we  can  say  with  confi 
dence  that  certain  pure  a  priori  synthetical  cognitions,  pure 
Mathematic  and  pure  Physic,  are  actual  and  given ;  for 


26  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [32-34 

both  contain  propositions,  which  are  thoroughly  recognised 
as  apodeictically  certain,  partly  by  mere  reason,  partly  by 
general  consent  [arising]  from  experience,  and  yet  as 
independent  of  experience.  .  We  have  therefore  some  at 
least  uncontested  synthetical  knowledge  a  priori,  and  need 
not  ask  if  it  be  possible  (for  it  is  actual),  but  possible,  in 
order  that  we  may  deduce  from  the  prin- [33]  ciple  which 
makes  the  given  cognitions  possible  the  possibility  of  all 
the  rest. 

The  General  Problem :  How  is  Cognition  from  Pure 
Reason  possible  ? 

§  5.  We  have  already  seen  the  vital  distinction  between 
analytical  and  synthetical  judgments.  The  possibility  of 
analytical  propositions  was  easily  comprehended,  being 
entirely  founded  on  the  law  of  Contradiction.  The  possi 
bility  of  synthetical  a  posteriori  judgments,  of  those  which 
are  gathered  from  experience,  likewise  requires  no  particular 
explanation ;  for  experience  is  nothing  but  a  continual 
synthesis  of  perceptions.  There  remain  therefore  only 
synthetical  propositions  a  priori,  of  which  the  possibility 
must  be  sought  or  investigated,  because  they  must  depend 
upon  other  principles  than  that  of  contradiction. 

But  we  have  no  right  to  seek  the  possibility  of  such 
propositions  here,  that  is,  to  inquire  whether  they  are 
possible.  For  there  are  enough  of  them  actually  given 
with  undoubted  certainty,  and  as  our  present  method  is 
analytical,  we  shall  start  from  the  assertion,  that  such 
synthetical  but  pure  cognition  of  the  reason  actually  exists ; 
but  we  must  then  inquire  into  the  ground  of  this  possibility, 
and  ask,  how  this  cognition  is  possible,  in  order  that  we 
may  [34]  from  the  principles  of  its  possibility  be  enabled  to 


34-351  PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION   27 

determine  the  conditions  of  its  use,  its  sphere  and  its 
bounds.  The  proper  problem  upon  which  all  depends, 
when  expressed  with  scholastic  precision,  is  therefore  : 

How  are  Synthetic  Propositions  a  priori  possible  ? 

For  the  sake  of  popularity  I  have  above  expressed  this 
problem  somewhat  differently,  as  an  inquiry  after  knowledge 
from  pure  reason,  and  this  I  could  do  for  once  without 
detriment  to  the  desired  view  [Einsicht],  because,  as  we 
have  only  to  do  here  with  metaphysic  and  its  sources,  the 
reader  will,  I  hope,  after  the  foregoing  remarks,  keep  in 
mind  that  when  we  speak  of  knowledge  from  pure  reason, 
we  do  not  mean  analytical,  but  always  synthetical  cog 
nition.1 

[35]  Upon  the  solution  of  this  problem  the  standing  or 
the  falling  of  Metaphysic  and  consequently  its  existence 
entirely  depend.  Let  any  one  make  assertions  ever  so 
plausible  with  regard  to  it, — let  him  pile  conclusions  upon 
conclusions  till  they  almost  smother  us, — if  he  has  not  been 
previously  able  to  answer  this  question  satisfactorily,  I  have 
a  right  to  say :  this  is  all  vain  groundless  philosophy  and 

1  As  knowledge  gradually  advances,  certain  expressions  now  classical, 
which  have  been  used  since  the  infancy  of  science,  cannot  but  be  found 
insufficient  and  unsuitable,  and  there  cannot  but  be  some  danger  of 
confusing  a  newer  and  more  appropriate  use  with  the  older.  The 
analytical  method,  so  far  as  it  is  opposed  to  the  synthetical,  is  very 
distinct  from  a  complex  of  analytical  propositions  :  it  signifies  only  that 
we  set  out  from  what  is  sought,  as  if  it  were  given,  and  ascend  to  the 
only  conditions  under  which  it  is  possible.  In  this  method  we  often  use 
nothing  but  synthetical  propositions,  as  in  mathematical  analysis,  and  it 
were  better  to  term  it  the  regressive  method,  in  contradistinction  to  the 
synthetic  or  progressive.  A  principal  part  of  Logic  too  is  distinguished 
by  the  name  of  Analytic,  which  here  signifies  the  logic  of  truth  (in 
contrast  to  Dialectic),  without  considering  whether  the  cognitions 
belonging  to  it  are  analytical  or  synthetical. 


28  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [35-36 

false  wisdom.  You  speak  through  pure  reason,  and  profess, 
as  it  were,  to  create  cognitions  a  priori  by  not  only  dis 
secting  given  concepts,  but  also  by  asserting  connexions 
which  do  not  rest  upon  the  principle  of  contradiction,  and 
which  you  profess  to  perceive  quite  independently  of  all  ex 
perience  ;  how  do  you  attain  this,  and  how  will  you  justify  your 
self  in  such  pretensions  ?  An  appeal  to  the  consent  of  the 
common  sense  of  mankind  cannot  be  allowed  ;  for  that  is  a 
witness  whose  reputation  depends  only  upon  public  rumour, 

Quodcunque  ostendis  mihi  sic,  incredulus  odi.  ' 

Indispensable,  however,  as  it  is  to  answer  this  question, 
it  is  equally  difficult  to  do  so ;  and  though  the  principal 
reason  that  this  answer  was  not  attempted  long  ago  is,  that 
the  possibility  of  such  a  question  [36]  never  occurred  to 
anybody,  there  is  yet  another  reason.  A  satisfactory  answer 
to  this  single  question  requires  a  much  more  constant,  pro 
found,  and  laborious  reflection,  than  the  most  diffuse  work 
on  Metaphysic,  which  on  its  first  appearance  promised 
immortality  to  its  author.  And  every  intelligent  reader, 
when  he  carefully  reflects  what  this  problem  requires,  must 
at  first  be  struck  with  its  difficulty,  and  would  regard  it  as 
insoluble  and  even  impossible,  did  there  not  actually  exist 
pure  synthetical  cognitions  a  priori.  This  actually  happened 
to  David  Hume,  though  he  did  not  represent  to  himself  the 
question  at  all  so  universally  as  is  done  here,  and  as  must 
be  done  if  the  answer  is  to  be  decisive  for  all  Metaphysic. 
For  how  is  it  possible,  says  that  acute  man,  that  when  a 
concept  is  given  me,  I  can  go  beyond  it  and  connect  with 
it  another,  which  is  not  contained  in  it,  and  in  such  a 
manner  as  if  the  latter  necessarily  belonged  to  the  former  ? 
Nothing  but  experience  can  furnish  us  with  connexions  of 
that  sort  (this  was  his  inference  from  that  difficulty,  which 


36-38]  PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION   29 

he  held  an  impossibility),  and  all  that  supposed  necessity,  or, 
what  is  the  same. thing,  all  cognition  a  priori  (held  to  be 
such),  is  nothing  but  a  long  habit  of  finding  something  true, 
and  hence  of  holding  subjective  necessity  to  be  objective. 

If  the  reader  should  complain  of  the  difficulty  and  the 
labour  which  I  occasion  him  in  the  solution  of  this  problem, 
let  him  endeavour  to  do  it  himself  [37]  in  an  easier  way. 
Perhaps  he  will  then  acknowledge  the  obligation  due  to  him 
who  has  undertaken  a  work  of  so  profound  research,  and 
will  rather  be  surprised  at  the  facility  with  which,  consider 
ing  the  nature  of  the  thing,  the  solution  has  been  attained. 
Yet  it  has  cost  a  labour  of  many  years  to  solve  this  problem 
in  its  whole  universality  (in  the  mathematical  sense,  that,  is, 
sufficient  for  all  cases),  and  finally  to  exhibit  it  in  the 
analytical  form,  as  the  reader  finds  it  here. 

All  metaphysicians  are  therefore  solemnly  and  legally  sus 
pended  from  their  occupations  till  they  shall  have  answered 
in  a  satisfactory  manner  the  question,  How  are  synthetic 
cognitions  a  priori  possible  ?  For  the  answer  contains  the 
only  credentials  which  they  must  show  when  they  have  any 
thing  to  bring  us  in  the  name  of  pure  reason.  But  if  they 
do  not  possess  these  credentials,  they  can  expect  nothing 
else  than  to  be  dismissed  without  further  inquiry  by  reason 
able  people,  who  have  already  been  so  often  deceived. 

If  they  on  the  other  hand  desire  to  carry  on  their  busi 
ness  not  as  a  science,  but  as  an  art  of  persuasion  wholesome 
and  suited  to  the  general  common  sense  of  man,  they  cannot 
in  justice  be  prevented.  They  will  then  speak  the  modest 
language  of  a  rational  faith,  they  will  grant  that  they  are  not 
allowed  even  to  conjecture,  far  less  to  know,  anything  which 
lies  beyond  the  bounds  of  all  possible  experience,  but  only 
[38]  to  assume  something  (not  for  speculative  use,  which 
they  must  abandon,  but  for  practical  only)  that  is  possible 


30  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [38-39 

and  even  indispensable  for  the  guidance  of  the  understanding 
and  of  the  will  in  life.  In  this  manner  only  can  they  bear 
the  title  of  useful  and  of  wise  men,  and  the  more  so  in  pro 
portion  as  they  renounce  that  of  metaphysicians ;  for  these 
will  be  speculative  philosophers,  and  as,  when  judgments  a 
priori  are  in  question,  poor  probabilities  cannot  be  admitted 
(for  what  is  pretended  to  be  known  a  priori  is  thereby 
announced  as  necessary),  such  men  cannot  be  permitted  to 
play  with  conjectures,  but  their  assertions  must  be  either 
science,  or  worth  nothing  at  all. 

It  may  be  said,  that  all  transcendental  philosophy,  which 
necessarily  precedes  all  Metaphysic,  is  nothing  but  the 
complete  solution  of  the  problem  here  propounded,  in 
systematical  order  and  completeness.  Hitherto  we  have 
accordingly  never  had  any  transcendental  philosophy ;  for 
what  goes  by  its  name  is  properly  a  part  of  Metaphysic ; 
whereas  the  former  science  is  intended  first  to  constitute  the 
possibility  of  this  latter,  and  must  therefore  precede  all 
Metaphysic.  And  it  is  not  surprising  that  when  a  whole 
science,  deprived  of  all  help  from  other  sciences,  and  conse 
quently  in  itself  quite  new,  is  required  to  answer  a  single 
question  sufficiently,  we  should  find  this  answer  combined 
with  trouble  and  difficulty,  nay  even  with  obscurity. 

[39]  As  we  now  proceed  to  this  solution,  and  according 
to  the  analytical  method,  in  which  we  presuppose,  that  such 
cognitions  from  pure  reason  actually  exist,  we  can  only 
appeal  to  two  sciences  of  theoretical  cognition  (as  such  only 
is  under  consideration  here),  pure  mathematic  and  the  pure 
science  of  nature  (physic).  For  none  but  these  can  exhibit 
objects  intuitively  to  us,  and  consequently  (if  there  should 
occur  in  them  a  cognition  a  priori]  can  show  the  truth  or 
harmony  of  the  cognition  with  the  object  in  concrete,  that  is, 
its  actuality,  from  which  we  could  then  proceed  to  the 


39-40]  PECULIARITIES  OF  METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION    31 

ground  of  its  possibility  by  analytic  procedure.  This 
method  facilitates  our  labour  greatly,  in  which  the  universal 
considerations  are  not  only  applied  to  facts,  but  even  set  out 
from  them,  instead  of  which  they  must  in  synthetic  pro 
cedure  be  entirely  derived  in  abstracto  from  concepts. 

But,  in  order  to  rise  from  these  actual  and  at  the  same 
time  well  grounded  pure  cognitions  a  priori  to  a  possible 
cognition  (which  we  are  seeking),  or  to  Metaphysic  as  a 
science,  it  is  necessary  for  us  to  comprehend  that  which 
occasions  it,  I  mean  the  mere  natural,  though  in  spite  of  its 
truth  not  unsuspected,  cognition  a  priori  which  lies  at  the 
basis  of  that  science,  the  elaboration  of  which  without  any 
critical  investigation  of  its  possibility  is  commonly  called 
metaphysic, — in  a  word,  we  must  comprehend  the  natural 
predisposition  to  such  a  science  under  our  chief  inquiry, 
and  thus  will  the  general  transcendental  [40]  problem, 
divided  into  four  other  questions,  be  gradually  answered  : 

1.  How  is  pure  mathematic  possible  ? 

2.  How  is  pure  physic  [science  of  nature]  possible  ? 

3.  How  is  metaphysic  in  general  possible  ? 

4.  How  is  metaphysic  as  a  science  possible  ? 

It  may  be  seen  that  the  solution  of  these  problems, 
though  chiefly  designed  to  exhibit  the  essential  matter  of 
the  Kritik,  has  yet  something  peculiar,  which  deserves  atten 
tion  in  itself.  This  is  the  seeking  the  sources  of  given 
sciences  in  the  reason  itself,  so  that  its  faculty  of  knowing 
something  a  priori  may  be  investigated  and  measured  by 
means  of  the  act  itself.  By  this  procedure  these  sciences 
themselves  gain,  if  not  with  regard  to  their  content,  yet  as 
to  their  right  use,  and  while  they  throw  light  on  the  higher 
question  concerning  their  common  origin,  at  the  same  time 
give  occasion  better  to  explain  their  individual  nature. 


[41]  FIRST  PART  OF  THE  GENERAL  TRAN 
SCENDENTAL  PROBLEM 

Hoiv  is  Pure  Mathematic  possible  ? 

§  6.  HERE  is  a  great  and  established  cognition,  which  em 
braces  even  now  a  wonderful  sphere,  and  bespeaks  here 
after  an  unbounded  extension,  which  carries  with  it 
thoroughly  apodeictical  certainty,  that  is,  absolute  necessity, 
which  therefore  rests  upon  no  empirical  grounds,  and 
consequently  is  a  pure  product  of  reason,  and  moreover  is 
thoroughly  synthetical.  '  How  then  is  it  possible  for  human 
reason  to  bring  to  pass  a  cognition  of  this  nature  entirely 
a  priori  ? '  Does  not  this  faculty,  as  it  neither  is  nor  can 
be  based  upon  experience,  presuppose  some  ground  of 
cognition  a  priori,  which  lies  deeply  hidden,  but  which 
might  reveal  itself  by  these'  its  effects,  if  their  first  begin 
nings  were  but  diligently  investigated  ? 

§  7.  But  we  find  all  mathematical  cognition  having  this 
peculiarity,  that  it  must  previously  exhibit  its  concept  in 
intuition  and  indeed  a  priori,  therefore  in  an  intuition  which 
is  not  empirical,  but  pure.  Without  this  process  Mathe 
matic  cannot  take  a  single  [42]  step;  hence  its  judgments 
are  always  intuitive ;  whereas  philosophy  must  be  satisfied 
with  discursive  judgments  from  mere  concepts,  and  though  it 
may  illustrate  its  doctrines  by  intuition,  can  never  derive  them 


42-43]      HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATIC  POSSIBLE?  33 

from  it.  This  observation  on  the  nature  of  Mathematic 
gives  us  a  clue  to  the  first  and  highest  condition  of  its 
possibility,  which  is,  that  some  pure  intuition  must  form  its 
basis,  in  which  all  its  concepts  can  be  exhibited  or  con 
structed,  in  concrete  and  yet  a  priori.  If  we  can  find  out 
this  pure  intuition  and  its  possibility,  we  may  thence 
easily  explain  how  synthetical  propositions  a  priori  are 
possible  in  pure  mathematic,  and  consequently  how  this 
science  itself  is  possible.  Empirical  intuition  enables  us 
without  difficulty  to  enlarge  the  concept  which  we  frame  of 
an  object  of  intuition,  by  new  predicates,  which  intuition 
itself  presents  synthetically  in  experience.  Pure  intuition 
does  so  likewise,  only  with  this  difference,  that  in  the  latter 
case  the  synthetical  judgment  is  a  priori  certain  and 
apodeictical,  in  the  former,  only  a  posteriori  and  empirically 
certain ;  because  this  latter  contains  only  what  occurs  in 
contingent  empirical  intuition,  but  the  former,  what  must 
be  met  in  pure  intuition  necessarily,  for  the  predicate  is 
inseparably  conjoined  as  intuition  a  priori  with  the  concept 
before  all  experience  or  individual  perception. 

§8.  But  with  this  step  our  perplexity  seems  rather  to 
increase  than  to  lessen.  For  the  question  [43]  now  is,  How 
is  it  possible  to  intuite  anything  a  priori  ?  An  intuition  is 
such  a  representation  as  immediately  depends  upon  the 
presence  of  the  object.  Hence  it  seems  impossible  origin 
ally  to  intuite  a  priori,  because  intuition  would  in  that 
event  take  place  without  either  a  former  or  a  present  object 
to  refer  to,  and  by  consequence  could  not  be  intuition. 
Concepts  indeed  are  such,  that  we  can  easily  form  some  of 
them  a  priori  (namely,  those  which  contain  nothing  but  the 
thinking  an  object  in  general),  without  finding  ourselves  in 
an  immediate  relation  to  the  object.  Such  are,  for  instance, 
the  concepts  of  Quantity,  of  Cause,  etc.  But  even  these 
H  p 


34  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [43-44 

require,  in  order  to  give  them  a  signification,  a  certain 
concrete  use — that  is,  an  application  to  some  intuition,  by 
which  an  object  of  them  is  given  us.  But  how  can  the 
intuition  of  the  object  precede  the  object  itself? 

§  9.  Were  intuition  of  such  nature  as  to  represent  things 
as  they  are  in  themselves,  intuition  could  not  take  place  a 
priori,  but  must  be  always  empirical.  For  I  can  only  know 
what  is  contained  in  the  object  in  itself  when  it  is  present 
and  given  to  me.  It  is  indeed  even  then  incomprehensible 
how  the  intuition  of  a  present  thing  should  make  me  know 
this  thing  as  it  is  in  itself,  as  its  properties  cannot  migrate  into 
my  faculty  of  representation ;  but  even  granting  this  possi 
bility,  an  intuition  of  that  sort  would  not  take  place  a  priori, 
that  is,  before  the  object  were  presented  to  me ;  for  without 
this  latter  [44]  fact  no  ground  of  relation  between  my 
representation  and  the  object  can  be  imagined:  it  must 
then  depend  upon  direct  inspiration  [Eingebung].  It  is 
therefore  only  possible  in  one  way  for  my  intuition  to 
anticipate  the  actuality  of  the  object,  and  to  be  cognition 
a  priori :  if  it  (the  intuition)  contains  nothing  but  the  form  of 
the  sensibility,  which  precedes  in  me  all  the  actual  impressions 
through  which  I  am  affected  by  objects.  For  I  can  know  a 
priori,  that  objects  of  sense  can  only  be  intuited  according 
to  this  form  of  the  sensuous  intuition.  Hence  it  follows  : 
that  propositions,  which  concern  this  form  of  sensuous 
intuition  only,  are  possible  and  valid  for  objects  of  the 
senses  ;  as  also,  conversely,  that  intuitions  which  are  possible 
a  priori  can  never  concern  any  other  things  than  objects 
of  our  senses. 

§  10.  It  is  then  only  the  form  of  sensuous  intuition  by 
which  we  can  intuite  things  a  priori,  but  by  which  we  can 
know  objects  only  as  they  appear  to  us  (to  our  senses),  not 
|as  they  are  in  themselves ;  and  this  assumption  is  absolutely 


44-46]       HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATIC  POSSIBLE  ?  35 

necessary  if  synthetical  propositions  a  priori  be  granted  as 
possible,  or  if,  in  case  they  actually  occur,  their  possibility  is 
to  be  comprehended  and  determined  beforehand. 

But  Space  and  Time  are  the  intuitions  which  pure 
Mathematic  lays  at  the  foundation  of  all  its  cognitions,  and 
of  the  judgments  which  appear  at  once  demonstrable  and 
necessary  ;  for  Mathematic  must  [45]  first  exhibit  all  its  con 
cepts  in  intuition,  and  pure  Mathematic  in  pure  intuition, 
that  is,  it  must  construct  them ;  otherwise  (as  it  cannot 
proceed  analytically,  by  dissection  of  concepts,  but  synthetic 
ally)  it  is  impossible  in  this  science  to  take  a  single  step. 
For  if  pure  intuition  be  wanting,  there  is  nothing  in  which 
the  matter  for  synthetical  judgments  a  priori  can  be  given. 
Geometry  is  based  upon  the  pure  intuition  of  space. 
Arithmetic  accomplishes  its  concept  of  number  by  the 
successive  addition  of  unities  in  time  ;  and  pure  Mechanic 
especially  cannot  attain  its  concepts  of  motion  without  em 
ploying  the  representation  of  time.1  Both  representations, 
however,  are  only  intuitions ;  for  if  we  omit  from  the  empir 
ical  intuitions  of  bodies  and  their  alterations  (motion)  every 
thing  empirical,  or  belonging  to  sensation,  space  and  time" 
still  remain,  which  are  therefore  pure  intuitions  that  lie  a 
priori  at  the  basis  of  the  empirical.  Hence  they  can  never 
be  omitted,  but  at  the  same  time,  by  their  [46]  being  pure  in-/ 
tuitions  a  priori,  they  prove  that  they  are  mere  forms  of  our 

1  The  form  of  this  statement,  which  makes  an  admission  nowhere 
supported  in  the  Kritik,  is  peculiar.  I  see  in  it  a  lurking  doubt  in 
Kant's  mind  whether  Arithmetic  may  not  be  derived  from  Time,  as  all 
'  his  commentators  believed.  He  feels  sure  about  Mechanic.  The 
reader  will  also  note  that  he  speaks  as  if  only  the  concept  of  number 
generally  were  so  derived.  This  is  certainly  true  of  the  schema  of 
quantity,  and  may  also  be  asserted  of  all  very  large  numbers,  which  we 
cannot  properly  imagine,  except  as  requiring  unfinished  acts  of  addition. 
Cf.  vol.  i.  p.  52.  M. 


36  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [46-47 

sensibility,  which  must  precede  all  empirical  intuition,  or 
perception  of  actual  objects,  and  conformably  to  which 
objects  can  be  known  a  priori,  but  only  as  they  appear 
to  us. 

§11.  The  problem  of  the  present  section  is  therefore 
solved.  Pure  mathematic,  as  synthetical  cognition  a  priori, 
is  only  possible  by  referring  to  no  other  objects  than  those 
of  the  senses.  At  the  basis  of  their  empirical  intuition  lies 
a  pure  intuition  (of  space  and  of  time)  a  priori.  This  is 
possible,  because  the  latter  intuition  is  nothing  but  the  mere 
form  of  the  sensitive  faculty,  which  precedes  the  actual 
appearance  of  the  objects,  in  that  it  in  fact  makes  them 
possible.  Yet  this  faculty  of  intuiting  a  priori  affects  not 
the  matter  of  the  phenomenon  (that  is,  the  sensation  in  it, 
for  this  constitutes  that  which  is  empirical),  but  its  form, 
viz.  space  and  time.  Should  any  man  venture  to  doubt 
that  these  are  determinations  adhering  not  to  things  in 
themselves,  but  to  their  relation  to  our  sensibility,  I  should 
be  glad  to  know  how  it  can  be  possible  to  know  a  priori 
(and  of  course  before  all  acquaintance  with,  or  presentation 
of,  things),  how  their  intuition  must  be  constituted ;  which 
however  is  here  the  case  with  space  and  time.  But  this  is 
quite  comprehensible  as  soon  as  both  count  for  nothing 
more  than  formal  conditions  of  our  sensibility,  while  the 
objects  count  merely  as  phenomena;  [47]  for  then  the 
jorm_of  the  phenomenon,  that  is,  the  pure  intuition,  can 
by  all  means  be  represented  us  proceeding  from  ourselves, 
that  is,  a  priori. 

§  1 2.  In  order  to  add  something  by  way  of  illustration  and 
confirmation,  we  need  only  attend  to  the  ordinary  and  neces 
sary  procedure  of  geometers.  All  proofs  of  the  complete 
equality l  of  two  given  figures  (where  the  one  can  be  com- 

1  As  distinguished  from  equivalence,  or  merely  equality  of  area.     M. 


47-4§]      HOW  IS  PURE  MATIIEMATIC  POSSIBLE  ?  37 

pletely  substituted  for  the  other)  come  ultimately  to  super 
position,  which  is  evidently  nothing  else  than  a  synthetical 
proposition  resting  upon  immediate  intuition,  and  this  intui 
tion  must  be  given  pure,  or  a  priori,  otherwise  the  proposition 
could  not  rank  as  apodeictically  certain,  but  would  have  em 
pirical  certainty  only.  It  could  only  be  said  that  it  is  always 
remarked  so,  and  holds  as  far  as  our  perception  reaches. 
That  complete  space  (which  is  itself  no  longer  the  boundary 
of  another  space)  has  three  dimensions,  and  that  space  in 
general  cannot  have  more,  is  based  on  the  proposition  that 
not  more  than  three  lines  can  intersect  at  right  angles  in 
one  point ;  but  this  proposition  cannot  by  any  means  be 
shown  from  concepts,  but  rests  immediately  on  pure  and  a 
priori  intuition,  because  it  is  apodeictically  certain.  That  we 
can  require  a  line  to  be  drawn  to  infinity  (in  indefinituni)^ 
a  series  [48]  of  changes  to  be  continued  (for  example,  spaces 
passed  ^through  by  motion)  in  indefinitum,  presupposes  a 
representation  of  space  and  time,  which  can  only  attach  to 
intuition,  namely,  so  far  as  it  in  itself  is  bounded  by  nothing, 
for  from  concepts  it  could  never  be  inferred.  Consequently 
Mathematic  is  actually  built  upon  pure  intuitions,  which  make 
its  synthetical  and  apodeictically  valid  propositions  possible, 
and  hence  our  transcendental  deduction  of  the  notions  of 
space  and  of  time  explains  at  the  same  time  the  possibility 
of  pure  mathematic,  which  may  be  conceded,  but  by  no 
means  explained,  without  some  such  deduction,  and  without 
our  assuming  '  that  everything  which  can  be  given  to  our 
senses  (to  the  external  sense  in  space,  the  internal  in  time) 
is  intuited  by  us  as  it  appears  to  us,  not  as  it  is  in  itself.' 

1  This  identification  of  unendlich  with  indefinitum  goes  far  to  corro 
borate  my  rendering  of  the  objectionable  phrase  in  the  Aesthetic,  which 
speaks  of  space  as  an  infinite  (unendlich)  given  quantity.  Cf.  vol.  i.  p. 
50,  note.  M. 


38  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [48-49 

§  1 3.  Those  who  cannot  yet  shake  off  the  notion  of  space 
and  time  being  actual  qualities  that  inhere  in  things  in  them 
selves,  may  exercise  their  acumen  on  the  following  paradox. 
When  they  have  in  vain  attempted  its  solution,  and  are  free 
from  prejudices  at  least  for  a  few  moments,  they  will  suspect 
that  the  degradation  of  space  and  of  time  to  mere  forms  of 
our  sensuous  intuition  may  perhaps  be  well  founded. 

When  two  things  are  quite  similar  in  all  the  points,  which 
can  be  known  of  each  separately  (in  all  the  determinations 
pertaining  to  quantity  and  to  [49]  quality),  it  must  follow, 
that  the  one  can  in  all  cases  and  relations  be  put  in  the 
place  of  the  other,  without  this  substitution  occasioning  the 
least  perceptible  difference.  This  in  fact  is  the  case  with 
plane  figures  in  geometry ;  but  various  spherical  figures 
exhibit,  notwithstanding  this  complete  internal  agreement, 
such  a  [limited]  one  in  their  external  relation,  that  the  one 
figure  cannot  possibly  be  put  in  the  place  of  the  other ;  for 
instance,  two  spherical  triangles  on  opposite  hemispheres, 
which  have  an  arc  of  the  equator  as  their  common  base, 
may  be  quite  equal,  both  as  regards  sides  and  angles,  so 
that  nothing  is  to  be  found  in  the  simple  and  complete 
description  of  the  one,  that  is  not  equally  in  the  description 
of  the  other,  and  yet  the  one  cannot  be  put  in  the  place  of 
the  other  (upon  the  opposite  hemisphere).  Here  is  then  an 
internal  difference  between  the  two  triangles,  which  difference 
no  understanding  can  describe  as  internal,  and  which  only 
manifests  itself  by  external  relations  in  space.  But  I  shall 
give  more  obvious  examples,  taken  from  common  life. 

What  can  be  more  similar  in  every  respect  to  my  hand 
and  to  my  ear,  or  in  every  part  more  alike,  than  their  images 
in  a  mirror  ?  And  yet  I  cannot  put  such  a  hand  as  is  seen 
in  the  glass  in  the  place  of  its  archetype ;  for  if  this  is  a 
right,  that  in  the  glass  is  a  left  hand,  and  the  image  or  re- 


49-51]       HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATIC  POSSIBLE?  39 

flection  of  the  right  ear  is  a  left  one  that  never  can  supply 
the    place    of    the    other.       Here   there   are    no   internal 
differences  [50]  which  any  understanding  could  perceive  by 
thought  alone ;  and  yet  the  differences  are  internal  as  far  as 
the  senses  teach,  for  the  left  hand  cannot  be  enclosed  in 
the  same  bounds  as  the  right,  notwithstanding  the  complete 
equality  and  similarity  of  both  (they  are  not  congruent) ; 
the  glove  of  one  hand  cannot  be  used  for  the  other.     What 
is  the  solution  ?     Those  objects  are  not  representations  of 
things  as  they  are  in  themselves,  and  as  the  pure  under 
standing  would  cognise  them,  but  sensuous  intuitions,  that 
is,  phenomena,  the  possibility  of  which  rests  upon  the  rela 
tion  of  certain  things  unknown  in  themselves  to  something 
else,  viz.  to  our  sensibility.     Space  is  the  form  of  the  ex 
ternal  intuition  of  this  sensibility,  and  the  internal  deter 
mination  of  every  [limited]  space  is  only  possible  by  the 
determination  of  its  external  relation  to  all  space,  of  which 
it  is  a  part  (in  other  words,  by  its  relation  to  the  external 
sense) ;  that  is,  the  part  is  only  possible  through  the  whole, 
which  is  never  the  case  with  things  in  themselves,  as  objects 
of  the  mere  understanding,  but  with  phenomena  only.     And 
hence  we  cannot  render  the  difference  between  similar  and 
equal  but  incongruous  things  (for  instance,  spirals  winding 
opposite  ways1)  intelligible  by  any  concept,  but  only  by  the 
relation  to  the  right  and  the  left   hand,  which  relates  im 
mediately  to  intuition. 

[51]  REMARK  I. 

Pure   Mathematic,   and  especially   pure  geometry,  can 
only  have  objective  reality  on  condition  of  its  referring  to 

1  Not  '  snails  rolled  up  contrary  to  all  sense,'  as  Mr.   Richardson 
has  it  ! 


4o  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [51-52 

objects  of  sense,  in  regard  to  which  the  principle  holds 
good,  that  our  sensuous  representation  is  a  representation 
not  of  things  in  themselves,  but  of  the  way  in  which  they 
appear  to  us.  Hence  it  follows,  that  the  propositions  of 
geometry  are  not  the  determinations  of  a  mere  creation  of 
our  poetic  fancy,  which  therefore  cannot  be  referred  with 
certainty  to  actual  objects ;  but  rather  that  they  are  neces 
sarily  valid  of  space,  and  consequently  of  all  that  may  be 
found  in  it,  because  space  is  nothing  else  than  the  form  of  all 
external  phenomena,  in  which  [form]  alone  objects  of  sense 
can  be  given.  Sensibility  (of  which  the  form  is  the  basis 
of  geometry)  is  that  upon  which  the  possibility  of  external 
phenomena  rests ;  these  therefore  can  never  contain  any 
thing  but  what  geometry  prescribes  to  them.  It  would  be 
quite  otherwise  if  the  senses  were  so  constituted  as  to 
represent  objects  as  they  are  in  themselves.  For  then  it 
would  not  by  any  means  follow  from  the  representation  of 
space,  which  the  geometer  makes  his  a  priori  foundation, 
with  all  its  properties,  that  this  space,  together  with  what  is 
thence  inferred,  must  be  so  in  nature.  The  space  of  the 
geometer  would  be  considered  a  mere  fiction,  and  no 
objective  validity  ascribed  to  it,  because  we  cannot  see  how 
things  [52]  must  of  necessity  agree  with  an  image  of  them, 
which  we  make  spontaneously  and  previous  to  our  per 
ception  of  them.  But  if  this  image,  or  rather  this  formal 
intuition,  is  the  essential  property  of  our  sensibility,  by 
means  of  which  alone  objects  are  given  to  us,  and  if  this 
sensibility  represents  not  things  in  themselves,  but  phe 
nomena — then  it  is  very  easy  to  comprehend,  and  at  the 
same  time  to  prove  indisputably,  that  all  the  external 
objects  of  our  world  of  sense  must  necessarily  accord 
strictly  with  the  propositions  of  geometry;  because  the 
sensibility  by  means  of  its  form  of  external  intuition  (in 


52-53]       HOW  IS  PURE  MATIIEMATIC  POSSIBLE?  41 

other  words,  by  space,  with  which  the  geometer  is  occu 
pied),  first  of  all  makes  those  objects  possible  as  mere 
appearances.  It  will  always  remain  a  remarkable  feature 
in  the  history  of  philosophy,  that  there  was  once  a  time, 
when  even  mathematicians,  who  were  philosophers  too, 
began  to  doubt,  not  of  the  accuracy  of  their  geometrical 
propositions  so  far  as  they  concerned  space,  but  of  the 
objective  validity  and  the  applicability  of  this  concept  itself, 
and  of  all  its  determinations,  to  nature.  They  were  appre 
hensive  that  a  line  in  nature  might  consist  of  physical 
points,  and  consequently  that  true  space  in  the  object  might 
consist  of  simple  parts,  though  the  space  which  the  geo 
meter  has  in  his  mind  cannot  be  such.  They  did  not 
recognise  that  this  mental  space  makes  the  physical  space, 
that  is,  the  extension  of  matter,  even  possible ;  that  this 
pure  space  is  not  at  all  a  [53]  quality  of  things  in  them 
selves,  but  a  form  of  our  sensuous  faculty  of  representation  ; 
and  that  all  objects  in  space  are  mere  phenomena,  that 
is,  not  things  in  themselves  but  representations  of  our 
sensuous  intuition.  Space,  therefore,  as  the'  geometer 
conceives  it,  is  strictly  the  form  of  sensuous  intuition  which 
we  find  a  priori  in  us,  and  contains  the  ground  of  the 
possibility  of  all  external  phenomena  (as  to  their  form),  so 
that  these  must  necessarily  and  accurately  agree  with  the 
propositions  of  the  geometer,  which  he  draws  not  from  any 
imaginary  concept,  but  from  the  subjective  basis  of  all 
external  phenomena,  which  is  the  sensibility  itself.  In  this 
and  no  other  way  can  Geometry  be  secured  (as  to  the 
undoubted  objective  reality  of  its  propositions)  from  all  the 
juggling  of  shallow  Metaphysic,  however  surprising  it  may 
seem  to  this  science,  because  it  has  not  reverted  to  the 
sources  of  its  concepts. 


42  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [53-54 


REMARK  II. 

Whatever  is  given  us  as  object,  must  be  given  us  in 
intuition.  All  our  intuition  however  takes  place  by  means 
of  the  senses  only ;  the  understanding  intuites  nothing,  but 
only  reflects.1  And  as  we  have  [54]  just  shown  that  the 
senses  never  and  in  no  manner  enable  us  to  know  things  in 
themselves,  but  only  their  phenomena,  which  are  mere 
representations  of  the  sensibility,  we  conclude  that  'all 
bodies,  together  with  the  space  in  which  they  are,  must  be 
considered  nothing  but  mere  representations  in  us,  and  exist 
nowhere  but  in  our  thoughts.'  You  will  say  :  Is  not  this 
manifest  idealism  ? 

Idealism  consists  in  the  assertion,  that  there  are  none 
but  thinking  beings,  all  other  things,  which  we  think  are 
perceived  in  intuition,  being  nothing  but  representations  in 
the  thinking  beings,  to  which  no  object  external  to  them 
corresponds  in  fact.  Whereas  I  say,  that  things  as  objects 
of  our  senses  existing  outside  us  are  given,  but  we  know 
nothing  of  what  they  may  be  in  themselves,  knowing  only 
their  phenomena,  that  is,  the  representations  which  they 
cause  in  us  by  affecting  our  senses.  Consequently  I  grant 
by  all  means  that  there  are  bodies  without  us,  that  is,  things 
which,  though  quite  unknown  to  us  as  to  what  they  are 
in  themselves,  we  yet  know  by  the  representations  which 
their  influence  on  our  sensibility  procures  us,  and  which  we 
call  bodies,  a  term  signifying  merely  the  appearance  of  the 
thing  which  is  unknown  to  us,  but  not  therefore  less 

1  This,  and  a  dozen  other  such  passages,  should  have  kept  Mr. 
Lewes  (Hist,  of  Phil.  ii.  p.  515)  from  putting  the  vaguely-worded 
question  :  «  Did  Kant  mean  that  man  has  intuitive  Reason  ? '  and  still 
more  from  answering  it  in  exactly  the  reverse  way  to  what  Kant  would 
have  done.  M. 


54-56]      HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATIC  POSSIBLE  ?  43 

actual.1     Can  this  be  termed  idealism  ?      It   is   the  very 
contrary. 

[55]  All  this  had  been  generally  assumed  and  granted 
long  before  Locke's  time,  and  still  more  generally  ever 
since — that,  without  detriment  to  the  actual  existence  of 
external  things,  many  of  their  predicates  may  be  said  to 
belong  not  to  the  things  in  themselves,  but  to  their 
phenomena,  and  to  have  no  proper  existence  outside  our 
representation.  Heat,  colour,  and  taste,  for  instance,  are 
of  this  kind.  But  that  I  should  go  farther,  and  rank  as 
mere  phenomena,  for  weighty  reasons,  the  remaining  quali 
ties  of  bodies  also,  which  are  called  primary,  such  as 
extension,  place,  and  in  general  space,  with  all  which 
belongs  to  it  (impenetrability  or  materiality,  figure,  etc.) — 
against  this  proceeding  no  one  can  contend  with  any  reason 
that  it  is  inadmissible.  As  little  as  the  man  who  admits 
colours  not  to  be  properties  of  the  object  in  itself,  but  only 
modifications  of  the  sense  of  seeing,  can  on  that  account 
be  named  an  idealist,  so  little  can  my  system  be  named 
idealistic,  merely  because  I  find  that  more,  nay,  that  all  the 
properties  which  constitute  the  intuition  of  a  body  belong 
merely  to  its  phenomenon ;  for  the  existence  of  the  thing 
that  appears  is  thereby  not  destroyed,  as  in  true  idealism, 
but  it  is  only  shown,  that  we  cannot  possibly  know  it  by 
the  senses  as  it  is  in  itself. 

[56]  I  should  be  glad  to  know  what  my  assertions  must 
be  in  order  to  avoid  all  idealism.  I  suppose  I  must  say, 
not  only  that  the  representation  of  space  is  perfectly  con 
formable  to  the  relation  which  our  sensibility  has  to  objects 

1  This  statement  is  more  explicit  than  anything  in  the  Kritik,  and 
settles  the  question  as  to  Kant's  supposed  idealism.  Had  his  First 
Edition  really  differed  from  this  exposition,  he  would  never  have  sug 
gested  to  his  readers  a  comparison  with  the  Second.  M. 


44  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [56-57 

— for  that  I  have  said — but  also  that  it  is  quite  similar  to 
them ;  an  assertion  in  which  I  can  find  as  little  meaning  as 
if  I  said  that  the  sensation  of  red  has  a  similarity  to  the 
property  of  vermilion,  which  excites  this  sensation  in  me. 


REMARK  III. 

Hence  we  may  at  once  obviate  an  easily  foreseen  but 
worthless  objection,  '  that  by  admitting  the  ideality  of  space 
and  of  time  the  whole  sensible  world  would  be  turned 
into  mere  illusion.'  For  men  had  at  first  spoiled  all 
philosophical  insight  into  the  nature  of  sensuous  cognition, 
by  making  the  sensibility  merely  a  confused  mode  of 
representation,  according  to  which  we  still  know  things  as 
they  are,  but  without  being  able  to  bring  everything  in  this 
our  representation  to  a  clear  consciousness ;  whereas  we 
had  proved,  that  sensibility  consists  not  in  this  logical 
distinction  of  clearness  and  obscurity,  but  in  the  genetical 
one  of  the  origin  of  cognition  itself.  For  sensuous  cogni 
tion  represents  things  not  at  all  as  they  are,  but  only  the 
mode  in  which  they  affect  our  senses,  and  consequently  by 
it  phenomena  only  and  not  things  themselves  are  [57]  given 
to  the  understanding  for  reflection.  After  this  necessary  cor 
rection,  an  objection  is  mooted  arising  from  an  unpardon 
able  and  almost  intentional  misconception,  as  if  my  system 
turned  all  the  things  of  the  world  of  sense  into  mere  illusion. 

When  an  appearance  is  given  us,  we  are  still  quite  free 
as  to  our  judgment  on  the  matter.  The  phenomenon 
depends  upon  the  senses,  but  the  judgment  upon  the  under 
standing,  and  the  only  question  is,  whether  in  the  determina 
tion  of  the  object  there  is  truth  or  not.  But  the  difference 
between  truth  and  dreaming  is  not  ascertained  by  the  nature 
of  the  representations,  which  are  referred  to  objects  (for 


57-58]       HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATIC  POSSIBLE  ?  45 

they  are  the  same  in  both  cases),  but  by  their  connexion 
according  to  those  rules,  which  determine  the  coherence  of 
the  representations  in  the  concept  of  an  object,  and  by 
ascertaining  whether  they  can  subsist  together  in  experience 
or  not.  And  it  is  not  the  fault  of  the  phenomena  if  our 
cognition  takes  illusion  for  truth,  that  is,  if  the  intuition,  by 
which  an  object  is  given  us,  is  considered  a  concept  of  the 
thing  or  of  its  existence  also,  which  the  understanding  can 
only  think.  The  senses  represent  to  us  the  paths  of  the 
planets  as  now  forward,  now  backward,  and  herein  is  neither 
falsehood  nor  truth,  because  as  long  as  we  hold  this  path  to 
be  nothing  but  appearance,  we  do  not  judge  of  the  objective 
nature  of  their  motion.  But  as  a  false  judgment  may  easily 
arise  when  the  understanding  does  not  carefully  guard  [58] 
against  this  subjective  mode  of  representation  being  con 
sidered  objective,  we  say  they  appear  to  move  backward  ;  it 
is  not  the  senses  however  which  are  charged  with  the 
illusion,  but  the  understanding,  whose  province  alone  it  is 
to  give  an  objective  judgment  on  the  phenomenon. 

Thus,  even  if  we  did  not  at  all  reflect  on  the  origin  of  our 
representations,  and  [merely]  connect  our  intuitions  of  sense 
(whatever  they  may  contain),  in  space  and  in  time,  according 
to  the  rules  of  the  coherence  of  all  cognition  in  experience, 
[still]  illusion  or  truth  may  arise  according  as  we  are 
negligent  or  careful ;  it  is  merely  a  question  of  the  use  of 
sensuous  representations  in  the  understanding,  and  not  of 
their  origin.  Again — when  I  consider  all  the  representa 
tions  of  the  senses,  together  with  their  form,  space  and  time, 
to  be  nothing  but  phenomena,  and  space  and  time  to  be 
a  mere  form  of  the  sensibility,  which  is  not  to  be  met  with 
in  objects  out  of  it,  and  when  I  make  use  of  these  repre 
sentations  in  reference  to  possible  experience  only — there  is 
nothing  therein  that  can  lead  to  error,  nor  is  there  any 


46  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [58-60 

illusion  implied  in  my  holding  them  mere  phenomena ;  for 
they  can  notwithstanding  cohere  rightly  according  to  rules 
of  truth  in  experience.  Thus  all  the  propositions  of 
geometry  hold  good  of  space  as  well  as  of  all  the  objects  of 
the  senses,  consequently  of  all  possible  experience,  whether 
I  consider  space  as  a  mere  form  of  the  sensibility,  or  as 
something  [59]  cleaving  to  the  things  themselves.  It  is 
only  in  the  former  case  that  I  can  comprehend  how  it  is 
possible  to  know  these  propositions  of  all  the  objects  of  ex 
ternal  intuition  a  priori ;  everything  else  which  regards  all 
possible  experience  remains  just  as  if  I  had  not  seceded 
from  the  common  opinion. 

But  if  I  venture  to  go  beyond  all  possible  experience 
with  my  notions  of  space  and  time,  which  I  cannot  avoid 
doing  if  I  proclaim  them  qualities  which  adhere  to  things  in 
themselves  (for  what  can  prevent  my  letting  them  hold 
good  of  the  same  things,  however  my  senses  might  be 
changed,  and  whether  they  were  suited  to  them  or  not  ?), 
then  a  grave  error  resting  upon  an  illusion  may  arise.  For  I 
proclaim  to  be  universally  valid  what  is  merely  a  subjective 
condition  of  the  intuition  of  things  and  sure  for  all  objects 
of  sense,  but  therefore  only  valid  for  all  possible  experience  ; 
since  in  doing  so,  I  refer  this  condition  to  things  in  them 
selves,  and  do  not  limit  it  to  the  conditions  of  experience. 

My  theory  of  the  ideality  of  space  and  of  time,  therefore, 
so  far  from  reducing  the  whole  sensible  world  to  mere 
illusion,  is  rather  the  only  means  of  securing  the  application 
of  one  of  the  most  important  cognitions  (that  which  mathe- 
matic  propounds  a  priori]  to  actual  objects,  and  of  pre 
venting  its  being  regarded  mere  illusion.  For  without  this 
observation  it  would  be  quite  impossible  to  make  out 
whether  the  intuitions  of  space  and  time,  which  we  borrow 
from  [60]  no  experience,  and  which  yet  lie  in  our  repre- 


60-61]      HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATIC  POSSIBLE  ?  47 

sentation  a  priori,  are  not  mere  chimeras  of  our  brain,  to 
which  no  object  whatever  corresponds,  at  least  adequately, 
and  consequently,  whether  geometry  itself  is  not  a  mere 
illusion,  whereas  we  have  been  able  to  show  its  unquestion 
able  validity  with  regard  to  all  the  objects  of  the  sensible 
world  because  they  are  mere  phenomena. 

Secondly :  These  my  principles,  because  they  make 
phenomena  of  the  representations  of  the  senses,  are  so  far 
from  turning  the  truth  of  experience  into  mere  illusion,  that 
they  are  rather  the  only  means  of  preventing  the  transcend 
ental  illusion,  by  which  Metaphysic  has  hitherto  been 
deceived,  and  led  to  the  childish  endeavour  of  catching  at 
bubbles,  while  phenomena,  which  are  mere  representations, 
were  taken  for  things  in  themselves — an  error  which  gave 
occasion  to  the  remarkable  Antinomy  of  Reason  that  I  shall 
mention  by  and  by,  and  which  is  destroyed  by  the  single 
observation,  that  phenomenon,  as  long  as  it  is  used  in  ex 
perience,  produces  truth,  but  the  moment  it  transgresses  the 
bounds  of  experience,  and  consequently  becomes  transcend 
ent,  produces  nothing  but  illusion. 

As  I  therefore  leave  to  things  as  we  obtain  them  by  the 
senses  their  actuality,  and  only  limit  our  sensuous  intuition 
of  these  things  to  this,  that  they  represent  in  no  respect, 
not  even  in  the  pure  intuitions  of  space  and  of  time,  any 
thing  more  than  [61]  mere  appearances  of  those  things,  but 
never  their  constitution  in  themselves,  this  is  not  a  thorough 
going  illusion  invented  for  nature  by  me.  My  protesta 
tion  too  against  all  charges  of  idealism  is  so  valid  and  clear 
as  even  to  seem  superfluous,  were  there  not  incompetent 
judges,  who,  while  they  would  have  an  old  name  for  every 
deviation  from  their  perverse  though  common  opinion,  and 
never  judge  of  the  spirit  of  philosophic  nomenclature,  but 
cling  to  the  letter  only,  are  ready  to  put  their  own  conceits 


48  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [61-62 

in  the  place  of  well-determined  notions,  and  thereby  deform 
and  distort  them.  For  my  having  given  this  my  theory  the 
name  of  transcendental  idealism,  can  authorise  no  one  to 
confound  it  with  the  empirical  idealism  of  Descartes. 
(Indeed  his  was  only  an  insoluble  problem,  owing  to  which 
he  thought  every  one  at  liberty  to  deny  the  existence  of  the 
corporeal  world,  as  it  never  could  be  proved  satisfactorily.) 
Nor  [does  it  justify  a  confusion]  with  the  mystical  and 
visionary  idealism  of  Berkeley,  against  which  and  other 
similar  chimeras  our  Kritik  rather  contains  the  proper  anti 
dote.  For  my  idealism  concerns  not  the  existence  of  things 
(the  doubting  of  which  however  constitutes  idealism  in  the 
ordinary  sense),  since  it  never  came  into  my  head  to  doubt 
them,1  but  it  concerns  the  sensuous  [62]  representation  of 
things,  to  which  space  and  time  especially  belong.  Of  these, 
consequently  of  all  phenomena  in  general,  I  have  only  shown, 
that  they  are  neither  things  (nor  determinations  belonging 
to  things  in  themselves),  but  mere  species  of  representation. 
But  the  word  'transcendental,'  which  with  me  means  a 
reference  of  our  cognition  not  to  things,  but  only  to  the 
cognitive  faculty ',  was  meant  to  obviate  this  misconception. 
Yet  rather  than  give  further  occasion  to  it  by  this  word,  I 
now  retract  it,  and  desire  this  idealism  of  mine  to  be  called 
critical.  But  if  it  be  really  an  objectionable  idealism  to 
convert  actual  things  (not  phenomena)  into  mere  representa 
tions,  by  what  denomination  shall  we  distinguish  that 
idealism  which  conversely  makes  things  of  mere  representa 
tions?  It  may,  I  think,  be  called  dreaming  idealism,  in 
contradistinction  to  the  former,  which  may  be  called 
visionary,  both  of  which  are  to  be  obviated  by  my  transcend 
ental,  or,  better,  critical  idealism. 

1  I  recommend  the  school  of  Kuno  Fischer  to  consider  this  plain 
utterance.     M. 


[63]  SECOND  PART  OF  THE  GENERAL  TRAN 
SCENDENTAL  PROBLEM 

Hoiv  is  the  Pure  Science  of  Nature  \Physic\  possible  ? 

§  14.  NATURE  is  the  existence  of  things,  so  far  as  it  is 
determined  according  to  universal  laws.  Should  nature 
signify  the  existence  of  things  in  themselves,  we  could  never 
cognise  nature  either  a  priori  or  a  posteriori.  Not  a  priori, 
for  how  can  we  know  what  belongs  to  things  in  themselves, 
since  this  never  can  be  done  by  the  dissection  of  our  con 
cepts  (analytical  judgments)  ?  For  we  do  not  want  to  know 
what  is  contained  in  our  concept  of  a  thing  (for  this  [content] 
belongs  to  its  logical  being),  but  what  is  in  the  actuality  of 
the  thing  superadded  to  our  concept,  and  by  what  the  thing 
itself  is  determined  in  its  existence  outside  the  concept. 
Our  understanding,  and  the  conditions  on  which  alone  it 
can  connect  the  determinations  of  things  in  their  existence, 
do  not  prescribe  any  rule  to  things  themselves ;  these  do 
not  conform  to  our  understanding,  but  it  must  conform 
itself  to  them ;  they  must  therefore  be  first  given  us  in 
order  to  gather  these  determinations  from  them,  wherefore 
they  would  not  be  cognised  a  priori. 

[64]  A  cognition  of  the  nature  of  things  in  themselves  a 
posteriori  would  be  equally  impossible.  For,  if  experience 
is  to  teach  us  laws,  to  which  the  existence  of  things  is 

II  E 


50  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPIIYSIC  [64-65 

subject,  these  laws,  if  they  regard  things  in  themselves,  must 
belong  to  them  of  necessity  even  outside  our  experience. 
But  experience  teaches  us  what  exists  and  how  it  exists,  but 
never  that  it  must  necessarily  exist  so  and  not  otherwise. 
Experience  therefore  can  never  teach  us  the  nature  of  things 
in  themselves. 

§  1 5.  We  nevertheless  actually  possess  a  pure  science  of 
nature  in  which  are  propounded,  a  priori  and  with  all  the 
necessity  requisite  to  apodeictical  propositions,  laws  to  which 
nature  is  subject.  I  need  only  call  to  witness  that  pro 
paedeutic  of  Physic  which,  under  the  title  of  the  universal 
Science  of  Nature,  precedes  all  Physic  (which  is  founded 
upon  empirical  principles).  In  it  we  have  Mathematic 
applied  to  phenomena,  and  also  merely  discursive  principles 
(or  those  derived  from  concepts),  which  constitute  the  philo 
sophical  part  of  the  pure  cognition  of  nature.  But  there 
are  several  things  in  it,  which  are  not  quite  pure  and  inde 
pendent  of  empirical  sources  :  such  as  the  concept  of  motion, 
that  of  impenetrability  (upon  which  the  empirical  concept  of 
matter  rests),  that  of  inertia,  and  many  others,  which  prevent 
its  being  called  a  perfectly  pure  science  of  nature.  Besides, 
it  only  refers  to  objects  of  the  external  sense,  and  therefore 
does  not  give  an  example  [65]  of  a  universal  science  of  nature, 
in  the  strict  sense,  for  such  a  science  must  reduce  nature  in 
general,  whether  it  regards  the  object  of  the  external  or  that 
of  the  internal  sense  (the  object  of  Physic  as  well  as 
Psychology),  to  universal  laws.  But  among  the  principles 
of  this  universal  Physic  there  are  a  few  which  actually  have 
the  required  universality  ;  for  instance,  the  propositions  that 
substance  is  permanent,  and  that  every  event  is  always 
previously  determined  by  a  cause  according  to  constant  laws, 
etc.  These  are  actually  universal  laws  of  nature,  which 
subsist  completely  a  priori.  There  is  then  in  fact  a  pure 


65-66]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OE  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  51 

science    of  nature,   and    the    question    arises,    How   is  it 
possible1} 

§  1 6.  The  word  nature  assumes  yet  another  meaning, 
which  determines  the  object,  whereas  it  (nature)  in  the  former 
[formal]  sense  only  denotes  the  conformity  to  law  \_Gesetz- 
mdssigkeif\  of  the  determinations  of  the  existence  of  things 
generally.  Nature  then  considered  materially  is  the  complex 
of  all  the  objects  of  experience.  And  with  this  only  are  we 
now  concerned,  for  besides,  things  which  can  never  be 
objects  of  experience,  if  they  must  be  cognised  as  to  their 
nature,  would  oblige  us  to  have  recourse  to  concepts  whose 
meaning  could  never  be  given  in  concreto  (by  any  example 
of  possible  experience).  Consequently  we  must  form  for 
ourselves  a  list  of  concepts  of  their  nature,  the  reality 
whereof — that  is,  whether  they  actually  refer  to  objects,  or 
are  mere  creatures  of  thought — could  never  be  determined. 
The  cognition  of  what  cannot  be  an  ob-[66]  ject  of  experi 
ence  would  be  hyperphysical,  and  concerning  this  the  sub 
ject  of  our  present  discussion  has  nothing  to  say,  but  only 
concerning  the  cognition  of  nature,  the  reality  of  which 
[cognition]  can  be  confirmed  by  experience,  though  it  is 
possible  a  priori  and  precedes  all  experience. 

§  17.  The  formal  [side]  of  nature  in  this  narrower  sense 
is  therefore  the  conformity  to  law  of  all  the  objects  of  ex 
perience,  and  so  far  as  it  is  cognised  a  priori,  their  necessary 
conformity.  But  it  has  been  just  shown  that  the  laws  of 
nature  can  never  be  cognised  a  priori  in  objects  so  far  as 
they  are  considered  not  in  reference  to  possible  experience, 
but  as  things  in  themselves.  And  our  inquiry  here  extends 
not  to  things  in  themselves  (the  properties  of  which  we  pass 
by),  but  to  things  as  objects  of  possible  experience,  and  the 
complex  of  these  is  what  we  properly  designate  as  nature. 
And  now  I  ask,  when  the  possibility  of  a  cognition  of  nature 


52  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [66-67 

a  priori  is  in  question,  whether  it  is  better  to  arrange  the 
problem  thus  :  How  could  we  cognise  a  priori  that  things  as 
objects  of  experience  necessarily  conform  to  law  ?  or  thus  : 
How  is  it  possible  to  cognise  a  priori  ti\z  necessary  conformity 
to  law  of  experience  itself  as  regards  all  its  objects  gener 
ally? 

When  examined,  the  solution  of  the  problem,  represented 
in  either  way,  amounts,  with  regard  to  the  pure  cognition  of 
nature  (which  is  the  point  of  the  question  [67]  at  issue), 
entirely  to  the  same  thing.  For  the  subjective  laws,  under 
which  alone  an  empirical  cognition  of  things  is  possible,  hold 
good  of  these  things,  as  objects  of  possible  experience  (not 
as  things  in  themselves,  which  are  not  considered  here).  It 
is  quite  the  same  whether  I  say  :  Without  the  law,  that  when 
an  event  is  perceived,  it  is  always  referred  to  something  that 
precedes,  which  it  follows  according  to  a  universal  rule, 
[without  this  law]  a  perceptive  judgment  never  can  rank  as 
experience ;  or  whether  I  express  myself  thus  :  All,  of  which 
experience  teaches  that  it  happens,  must  have  a  cause. 

It  is,  however,  better  to  choose  the  first  formula.  For  we 
can  a  priori  and  previous  to  all  given  objects  have  a  cogni 
tion  of  those  conditions,  on  which  alone  experience  with 
regard  to  such  objects  is  possible,  but  never  of  the  laws  to 
which  they  may  in  themselves  be  subject,  without  reference 
to  possible  experience.  We  cannot  therefore  study  the  nature 
of  things  a  priori  otherwise  than  by  investigating  the  condi 
tions  and  the  universal  (though  subjective)  laws,  under  which 
alone  such  a  cognition  as  experience  (as  to  mere  form)  is 
possible,  and  we  determine  accordingly  the  possibility  of 
things,  as  objects  of  experience.  For  if  I  should  choose  the 
second  formula,  and  seek  the  conditions  a  priori,  on  which 
nature  as  an  object  of  experience  is  possible,  I  might  easily  fall 
into  error,  and  fancy  that  I  was  speaking  of  nature  as  a  thing 


68-69]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  53 

[68]  in  itself,  and  then  be  endlessly  toiling  in  search 
of  laws  for  things  of  which  nothing  is  given  me. 

Consequently  we  shall  here  be  concerned  with  experience 
only,  and  the  universal  conditions  given  a  priori  of  its 
possibility,  and  we  shall  thence  determine  nature  as  the 
whole  object  of  all  possible  experience.  I  think  it  will  be 
understood  that  I  here  do  not  mean  the  rules  of  the  observa 
tion  of  a  nature  that  is  already  given,  for  these  already  pre 
suppose  experience ;  that  I  do  not  therefore  mean  how  we 
(by  experience)  can  learn  from  nature  her  laws ;  for  these 
would  not  then  be  laws  a  priori,  and  would  yield  us  no  pure 
science  of  nature ;  but  [I  mean  to  inquire]  how  the  condi 
tions  a  priori  of  the  possibility  of  experience  are  at  the  same 
time  the  sources  from  which  all  the  universal  laws  of  nature 
must  be  derived. 

§  18.  We  must  then  in  the  first  place  observe  that,  though 
all  judgments  of  experience  are  empirical — that  is,  have 
their  ground  in  the  immediate  perception  of  the  senses — 
all  empirical  judgments  are  not  therefore  conversely  judg 
ments  of  experience,  but  that,  besides  the  empirical,  and 
in  general  besides  what  is  given  to  the  sensuous  intui 
tion,  particular  concepts  must  yet  be  superadded — concepts 
which  have  their  origin  quite  a  priori  in  the  pure  under 
standing,  and  under  which  every  perception  must  be  first 
of  all  subsumed  and  then  by  their  means  changed  into  ex 
perience. 

[69].  Empirical  judgments,  so  far  as  they  have  objective 
validity,  are  JUDGMENTS  OF  EXPERIENCE  ;  but  those  which 
are  only  subjectively  valid,  I  name  mere  JUDGMENTS  OF 
PERCEPTION.  The  latter  require  no  pure  concept  of  the 
understanding,  but  only  the  logical  connexion  of  perception 
in  a  thinking  subject.  But  the  former  always  require, 
besides  the  representation  of  the  sensuous  intuition, 


54  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [69-70 

rf  particular  concepts  originally  begotten  in  the  understanding, 
|  which  produce  the  objective  validity  of  the  judgment  of 
I'  experience. 

All  our  judgments  are  at  first  mere  perceptive  judgments  ; 
they  hold  good  merely  for  us  (that  is,  for  our  subject),  and 
we  do  not  till  afterwards  give  them  a  new  reference  (to  an 
object),  and  desire  that  they  shall  always  hold  good  for  us 
and  alike  for  everybody  else ;  for  when  a  judgment  agrees 
with  an  object,  all  judgments  concerning  the  same  object 
must  likewise  agree  among  themselves,  and  thus  the 
objective  validity  -of  the  judgment  of  experience  signifies 
nothing  else  than  its  ne^ejjSjj^Laiiuveisaii^^ 
And  conversely  when  we  have  reason  to  consider  a 
judgment  necessarily  universal  (which  never  depends  upon 
perception,  but  upon  the  pure  concept  of  the  understanding, 
under  which  the  perception  is  subsumed),  we  must  consider 
it  objective  also,  that  is,  that  it  expresses  not  merely  a 
reference  of  our  perception  to  a  subject,  but  a  quality  of  the 
object.  For  there  would  be  no  reason  for  the  judg-  [70] 
ments  of  other  men  necessarily  agreeing  with  mine,  if  it 
were  not  the  unity  of  the  object  to  which  they  all  refer,  and 
with  which  they  accord  ;  hence  they  must  all  agree  with  one 
another. 

§  19.  Objective  validity  therefore  and  necessary  univer 
sality  (for  everybody)  are  equivalent  notions,  and  though 
we  do  not  know  the  object  in  itself,  yet  when  we  consider 
a  judgment  as  universal,  and  also  necessary,  we  understand 
it  to  have  objective  validity.  By  this  judgment  we  cognise 
the  object  (though  it  remains  unknown  as  it  is  in  itself)  by 
the  universal  and  necessary  connexion  of  the  perceptions 
given  to  us.  As  this  is  the  case  with  all  objects  of  sense, 
judgments  of  experience  take  their  objective  validity  not 
from  the  immediate  cognition  of  the  object  (which  is 


70-7 1]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  55 

impossible),  but  from  the  condition  of  universal  validity  in 
empirical  judgments,  which,  as  already  said,  never  rests 
upon  empirical,  or,  in  short,  sensuous  conditions,  but  upon 
a  pure  concept  of  the  understanding.  The  object  always 
remains  unknown  in  itself;  but  when  by  the  concept  of  the 
understanding  the  connexion  of  the  representations  of  the 
object,  which  are  given  to  our  sensibility,  is  determined  as 
universally  valid,  it  (the  object)  is  determined  by  this 
relation,  and  the  judgment  is  objective. 

To  illustrate  the  matter:  that  the  room  is  warm,1  [71] 
sugar  sweet,  and  wormwood  bitter — these  are  merely 
subjectively  valid  judgments.  I  by  no  means  require,  that 
I  or  every  other  person  shall  always  find  them  true  as  I  now 
do ;  they  only  express  a  reference  of  two  sensations  to  the 
same  subject,  to  myself,  and  that  only  in  my  present  state 
of  perception  ;  consequently  they  are  not  valid  of  the  object; 
such  judgments  I  have  named  those  of  perception.  Judg 
ments  of  experience  are  of  quite  a  different  nature.  What 
experience  teaches  me  under  certain  circumstances,  it  must 
always  teach  me  and  everybody,  and  its  validity  I  do  not 
limit  to  the  subject  or  to  its  state  at  a  particular  time. 
Hence  I  pronounce  all  such  like  judgments  objectively 
valid.  For  instance,  when  I  say  the  air  is  elastic,  this 
judgment  is  as  yet  a  judgment  of  perception  only — I  do 

1  I  concede  at  once  that  these  examples  do  not  represent  such  judg 
ments  of  perception  as  ever  could  become  judgments  of  experience, 
even  though  a  concept  of  the  understanding  were  superadded,  because 
they  refer  merely  to  feeling,  which  everybody  knows  to  be  merely 
subjective,  and  which  of  course  can  never  be  attributed  to  the  object, 
and  consequently  never  become  objective.  I  only  wished  at  present  to 
give  an  example  of  a  judgment  that  is  merely  subjectively  valid,  and 
contains  in  itself  no  ground  for  universal  validity,  and  thereby  for  a 
reference  to  the  object.  An  example  of  the  judgments  of  perception, 
which  become  judgments  of  experience  by  superadded  concepts  of  the 
understanding,  will  be  given  in  the  next  note. 


56  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [71-73 

nothing  but  refer  two  of  my  sensations  to  one  another. 
But,  if  I  would  have  it  called  a  judgment  of  experience, 
I  require  this  connexion  to  stand  under  a  condition, 
which  makes  it  universally  valid.  I  desire  therefore 
[72]  that  I  and  everybody  else  should  always  conjoin 
necessarily  the  same  perceptions  under  the  same  circum 
stances. 

§  20.  We  must  consequently  analyse  experience  in 
general,  in  order  to  see  what  is  contained  in  this  product  of 
the  senses  and  of  the  understanding,  and  how  the  judgment 
of  experience  itself  is  possible.  The  foundation  is  conscious 
intuition,  that  is,  perception  (pcrceptid),  which  pertains 
merely  to  the  senses.  But  in  the  next  place,  judging  also 
(which  belongs  only  to  the  understanding)  pertains  thereto. 
But  this  judging  may  be  twofold — first,  in  that  I  merely 
compare  perceptions  and  conjoin  them  in  a  consciousness 
of  my  [particular]  state,  or  secondly,  in  that  I  conjoin  them 
in  consciousness  generally.  The  former  judgment  is  merely 
a  judgment  of  perception,  and  so  far  of  subjective  validity 
only  :  it  is  merely  a  connexion  of  perceptions  in  my  [present] 
mental  state,  without  reference  to  the  object.  Hence  it  is 
not,  as  is  commonly  imagined,  enough  for  experience  to 
compare  perceptions  and  to  connect  them  in  consciousness 
through  the  [comparative]  judgment ;  there  thus  arises  no 
universality  and  necessity  of  the  judgment,  by  which  alone 
it  can  be  objectively  valid  and  [become]  experience. 

Quite  another  judgment  therefore  is  required  before 
perception  can  become  experience.  The  given  intuition 
must  be  subsumed  under  a  concept,  which  determines  the 
fnp-n  nf  judging  \n  ganami  [yj]  HativHy  t"  intuition, 
connects  its  empirical  consciousness  in  consciousness 
gcncrallvr^and  thereby  procures  universal  validity  for 
empirical  judgments ;  a  concept  of  this  nature  is  a  pure  a 


73-74]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  57 

priori  concept  of  the  Understanding,  which  does  nothing 
but  determine  for  an  intuition  the  general  way  in  which  it 
can  serve  for  [the  process  of]  judging.  Suppose  the  concept 
of  cause  to  be  such,  then  it  determines  the  intuition  which 
is  subsumed  under  it,  e.g.  that  of  air,  relative  to  judging  in 
general,  so  that  the  concept  of  air  serves  with  regard  to  [its] 
expanding  [itself]  in  the  relation  of  the  antecedent  to  the 
consequent  in  a  hypothetical  judgment.  The  concept  of 
cause  then  is  a  pure  concept  of  the  understanding,  which 
is  totally  distinct  from  all  possible  perception,  and  only 
serves  to_determine  the  representation  contained  jundexutj 
relatively  to  judging  in^gejiejral,  and  so  to  make  a  universally 
valid  judgment  possible. 

Before,  therefore,  a  judgment  of  perception  can  become 
a  judgment  of  experience,  it  is  requisite  that  the  perception 
should  be  subsumed  under  such  a  concept  of  the  under 
standing  as  we  have  been  describing ;  for  instance,  air  ranks 
under  the  concept  of  causes,  which  determines  our  judgment 
about  it  in  regard  to  [its]  extending  [itself]  as  hypothetical.1 
[74]  But  this  extension  [extending]  is  thereby  represented 
not  as  merely  belonging  to  my  perception  of  the  air  in  my 
present  state  or  in  many  of  my  states  or  in  the  state  of 
perception  of  others,  but  as  belonging  to  this  perception  of 
necessity.  So  this  judgment,  'the  air  is  elastic,'  becomes 
universally  valid,  and  a  judgment  of  experience,  only  by 

1  As  an  easier  example,  we  may  take  the  following  :  'When  the  sun 
shines  on  the  stone,  it  grows  warm.'  This  judgment,  however  often  I 
and  others  may  have  perceived  it,  is  a  mere  judgment  of  perception, 
and  contains  no  necessity  ;  perceptions  are  only  usually  conjoined  in 
this  manner.  But  if  I  say,  '  The  sun  warms  the  stone,'  I  add  to  the 
perception  the  understanding-concept  \Verstandesbegriff'}  of  cause, 
which  necessarily  connects  with  the  concept  of  sunshine  that  of  heat, 
and  the  synthetical  judgment  becomes  of  necessity  universally  valid, 
consequently  objective,  and  is  converted  from  a  perception  into 
experience  [cf.  vol.  i.  p.  116,  note]. 


58  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [74-75 

certain  judgments  preceding  it,  which  subsume  the  intuition 
of  air  under  the  concept  of  cause  and  effect :  and  they 
thereby  determine  the  perceptions  not  merely  as  regards 
one  another  in  me,  but  relatively  to  the  form  of  judging  in 
general  (here  the  hypothetical),  and  in  this  way  they  render 
the  empirical  judgment  universally  valid.1 

If  all  our  synthetical  judgments  are  analysed  so  far  as 
they  are  objectively  valid,  it  will  be  found  that  they  never 
consist  of  mere  intuitions  connected  only  (as  is  commonly 
believed)  by  comparison  [75]  in  a  judgment;  but  that  they 
would  be  impossible  were  not  a  pure  concept  of  the  under 
standing  superadded  to  the  concepts  abstracted  from  intui 
tion,  under  which  concept  these  latter  are  subsumed,  and 
in  this  manner  only  connected  in  an  objectively  valid 
judgment.  Even  the  judgments  of  pure  Mathematic  in 
their  simplest  axioms  are  not  exempt  from  this  condition. 
The  principle,  '  a  straight  line  is  the  shortest  between  two 
points,'  presupposes  that  the  line  is  subsumed  under  the 
concept  of  quantity,  which  certainly  is  no  mere  intuition, 
but  has  its  seat  in  the  understanding  alone,  and  serves  to 
determine  the  intuition  (of  the  line)  with  regard  to  the 
judgments  which  may  be  made  about  it,  relatively  to  their 
quantity,  that  is,  to  plurality  (as  judicia  plurativd)?  For 

1  In  the  above  difficult  paragraph,  I  have  translated  Ausspannung 
and  Ausdthmmg  in  a  dynamical  and  not  in  a  statical  sense,  according 
to  Dr.  Toleken's  suggestion.  It  is  certainly  an  illustration  of  obscurum 
per  obscurius,  if  taken  in  any  other  way.  M. 

3  I  prefer  this  name  for  the  judgments,  which  are  termed  particular 
in  logic.  For  the  word  particular  seems  to  imply  the  notion  that  they 
are  not  universal.  But  when  I  begin  from  unity  (in  singular  judgments) 
and  so  proceed  to  universality,  I  must  not  imply  any  reference  to 
universality  :  I  think  of  plurality  merely  without  universality,  not  as 
its  exception.  This  distinction  is  necessary,  if  logical  distinctions 
[Momenti]  are  to  afford  the  basis  of  the  pure  concepts  of  the  under 
standing  :  in  logical  use  the  matter  is  not  worth  changing. 


75-76]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  59 

under  them  it  is  understood  that  in  a  given  intuition  there 
is  contained  a  plurality  of  homogenous  parts. 

§  21.  In  order  therefore  to  show  the  possibility  of 
experience  so  far  as  it  rests  upon  pure  concepts  of  [76]  the 
understanding  a  priori,  we  must  first  represent  what  belongs 
to  judging  generally,  and  the  various  phases  \Momente\  of 
the  understanding  in  [performing]  it,  in  a  complete  table. 
For  the  pure  understanding-concepts  must  run  parallel  to 
these  phases,  as  such  concepts  are  nothing  more  than 
concepts  of  intuitions  in  general,  so  far  as  these  are  deter 
mined  by  one  or  other  of  these  ways  of  judging,  in  them 
selves,  that  is,  necessarily  and  universally.  Hereby  also 
the  a  priori  principles  of  the  possibility  of  all  experience, 
as  of  an  objectively  valid  empirical  cognition,  will  be 
precisely  determined.  For  they  are  nothing  but  propositions 
by  which  all  perception  is  (under  certain  universal  conditions 
of  intuition)  subsumed  under  those  pure  concepts  of  the 
understanding. 


Logical  Table  of  Judgments. 

I.  2. 

As  to  Quantity.  As  to  Quality. 

Universal.  Affirmative. 

Particular  [plurative].  Negative. 

Singular.  Infinite. 

3-  4- 

As  to  Relation.  As  to  Modality. 

Categorical.  Problematical. 

Hypothetical.  ^  Assertorial. 

Disjunctive.  Apodeictical. 


60  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [77-7* 

[77]  Transcendental  Table  of  the  Pure  Concepts  of  the 
Under st a  nding. 

I.  2. 

As  to  Quantity.  As  to  Quality. 

Unity  (the  Measure).  Reality. 

Plurality  (the  Quantity).  Negation. 

Totality  (the  Whole).  Limitation. 

3-  4- 

As  to  Relation.  As  to  Modality. 
Substance.  Possibility. 

Cause.  Existence. 

Community.  Necessity. 

Pure  Physiological  Table  of  the  Universal  Principles 
of  the  Science  of  Nature. 

I-  2. 

Axioms  of  Intuition.  Anticipations  of  Perception. 

3- 
Analogies  of  Experience. 

4- 
Postulates  of  Empirical  Thinking  generally. 

§  2irt.  In  order  to  comprise  the  whole  matter  in  one 
notion,  it  is  first  necessary  to  remind  the  reader  that  we  are 
discussing  not  the  origin  of  experience,  but  of  that  which  lies 
in  experience.  The  former  pertains  to  empirical  psychology, 
and  would  even  [78]  then  never  be  adequately  explained 


78-79]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  61 

without  the  latter,  which  belongs  to  the  Kritik  of  cognition, 
and  particularly  of  the  understanding. 

Experience  consists  of  intuitions,  which  pertain  to  the 
sensibility,  and  of  judgments,  which  are  entirely  a  work  of 
the  understanding.  But  the  judgments,  which  the  under 
standing  forms  entirely  from  sensuous  intuitions,  are  far 
from  being  judgments  of  experience.  For  in  the  one  case 
the  judgment  connects  only  the  perceptions  as  they  are  given 
in  the  sensuous  intuition,  but  in  the  other  the  judgments 
are  to  express  what  experience  in  general,  and  not  what  the 
mere  perception,  with  its  subjective  validity,  contains. 
The  judgment  of  experience  must  therefore  add  to  the 
sensuous  intuition  and  its  logical  connexion  in  a  judgment 
(after  it  has  been  made  universal  by  comparison)  something 
that  determines  the  synthetical  judgment  as  necessary  and 
therefore  as  universally  valid.  This  can  be  nothing  else 
than  that  concept  which  represents  the  intuition  as  deter 
mined  in  itself  with  regard  to  one  form  of  judgment  rather 
than  another,1  which  [form]  is  a  concept  of  that  synthetical 
unity  of  intuitions  which  can  only  be  represented  by  a 
given  logical  function  of  judgments. 

§  22.  The  sum  of  the  matter  is  this  :  the  busi-  [79]  ness 
of  the  senses  is  to  intuite — that  of  the  understanding  is  to 
think.  But  thinking  means  uniting  representations  in  one 
consciousness.  This  union  is  either  merely  relative  to  the 
[individual]  subject,  and  is  contingent  and  subjective,  or  is 
absolute,  and  is  necessary  or  objective.  The  union  of 
representations  in  one  consciousness  is  judgment.  Think 
ing  therefore  is  the  same  as  judging,  or  referring  represent 
ations  to  judgments  in  general.  Hence  judgments  are 
either  merely  subjective,  when  representations  are  referred 

1  I  read  anderen^  being  unable  to  translate  andere  of  Rosencrantz's 
Edition.  M. 


62  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [79-80 

to  a  consciousness  in  one  subject  only,  and  united  in  it,  or 
objective,  when  they  are  united  in  a  consciousness  generally, 
that  is,  necessarily.  The  logical  phases  of  all  judgments 
are  but  various  modes  of  uniting  representations  in  con 
sciousness.  But  if  they  serve  for  concepts,  they  are  concepts 
of  their  necessary  union  in  a  consciousness,  and  so  principles 
of  objectively  valid  judgments.  This  union  in  a  conscious 
ness  is  either  analytical,  by  identity,  or  synthetical,  by  the 
combination  and  addition  of  various  representations  one  to 
another.  Experience  consists  in  the  synthetical  connexion 
of  phenomena  (perceptions)  in  consciousness,  so  far  as  this 
connexion  is  necessary.  Hence  the  pure  concepts  of  the 
understanding  are  those  under  which  all  perceptions  must 
be  subsumed  ere  they  can  serve  for  judgments  of  experience, 
in  which  the  synthetical  [80]  unity  of  the  perceptions  is 
represented  as  necessary  and  universally  valid.1 

§  23.  So  far  as  judgments  are  merely  considered  the 
condition  of  the  union  of  given  representations  in  a 
consciousness,  they  are  rules.  These  rules,  so  far  as  they 
represent  the  union  as  necessary,  are  rules  a  priori^  and  so 
far  as  they  cannot  be  deduced  from  higher  rules,  are 

1  But  how  does  this  proposition,  'that  judgments  of  experience 
contain  necessity  in  the  synthesis  of  perceptions,"  agree  with  my  state 
ment  so  often  before  inculcated,  that  '  experience  as  cognition  a  posteriori 
can  afiford  contingent  judgments  only  ?'  When  I  say  that  experience 
teaches  me  something,  I  mean  [by  experience]  only  the  perception  that 
lies  in  it— for  example,  that  heat  always  follows  the  shining  of  the  sun 
on  a  stone  ;  consequently  the  proposition  of  experience  is  always  so  far 
contingent.  That  this  heat  necessarily  follows  the  shining  of  the  sun 
is  contained  indeed  in  the  judgment  of  experience  (by  means  of  the 
concept  of  cause),  yet  is  a  fact  not  learned  by  experience;  for 
conversely,  experience  is  first  of  all  generated  by  this  addition  of  the 
concept  of  the  understanding  (of  cause)  to  perception.  How  perception 
attains  this  addition  may  be  seen  by  referring  in  the  Kritik  itself  to  the 
section  on  the  Transcendental  faculty  of  Judgment  [vol.  i.  pp.  144  sqq.] 


80-82]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  63 

fundamental  principles.  But  in  regard  to  the  possibility  of 
all  experience,  merely  in  relation  to  the  form  of  thinking  in 
it,  no  conditions  of  experience-judgments  are  higher  than 
those  which  bring  the  phenomena,  according  to  the  various 
form  of  their  intuition,  under  pure  concepts  of  the  under 
standing,  and  render  the  empirical  judgment  [81]  objectively 
valid.  These  concepts  are  therefore  the  a  priori  principles 
of  possible  experience. 

The  principles  of  possible  experience  are  then  at  the 
same  time  universal  laws  of  nature,  which  can  be  cognised 
a  priori.  And  thus  the  problem  in  our  second  question, 
How  is  the  pure  Science  of  Nature  possible  ?  is  solved.  For 
the  system  which  is  required  for  the  form  of  a  science  is  to 
be  met  with  in  perfection  here,  because,  beyond  the  above- 
mentioned  formal  conditions  of  all  judgments  in  general 
(viz.  of  all  the  general  rules  of  logic),  no  others  are  possible, 
and  these  constitute  a  logical  system.  The  concepts 
grounded  thereupon,  which  contain  the  a  priori  conditions 
of  all  synthetical  and  necessary  judgments,  accordingly 
constitute  a  transcendental  system.  Finally  the  principles, 
by  means  of  which  all  phenomena  are  subsumed  under 
these  concepts,  constitute  a  physiological  system,  that  is,  a 
system  of  nature,  which  precedes  all  empirical  cognition  of 
nature,  makes  it  even  possible,  and  hence  may  in  strictness 
be  denominated  the  universal  and  pure  science  of  nature. 

§  24.  The  first1  of  the  physiological  principles  subsumes 
all  phenomena,  as  intuitions  in  space  and  [82]  time,  under 
the  concept  of  Quantity,  and  is  so  far  a  principle  of  the 
application  of  Mathematic  to  experience.  By  the  second 

1  Without  referring  to  what  the  Kritik  itself  says  on  the  subject  of 
the  Principles,  the  three  following  paragraphs  will  not  be  well  under 
stood  ;  they  may,  however,  be  of  service  in  giving  a  general  view  of  the 
Principles,  and  in  fixing  the  attention  on  the  main  points. 


64  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [82-83 

that  which  is  empirical,  or  sensation,  which  denotes  what  is 
real  in  intuitions,  is  not  indeed  directly  subsumed  under 
the  concept  of  quantity,  because  sensation  is  not  an 
intuition  that  contains  either  space  or  time,  though  it  places 
the  object  related  to  itself  in  both.  But  still  there  is 
between  reality  (sensible  representation)  and  nothing,  or 
the  total  void  of  intuition  in  time,  a  difference  which  has  a 
quantity.  For  between  every  given  degree  of  light  and  of 
darkness,  between  every  degree  of  heat  and  of  absolute 
cold,  between  every  degree  of  weight  and  of  absolute 
lightness,  between  every  degree  of  occupied  space  and  of 
totally  void  space,  diminishing  degrees  can  be  conceived,  in 
the  same  manner  as  between  consciousness  and  total  un 
consciousness  (psychological  obscurity)  ever  diminishing 
degrees  find  their  place.  Hence  there  is  no  perception 
that  can  prove  an  absolute  want ;  for  instance,  no  psycho 
logical  obscurity  that  cannot  be  considered  as  a  [weaker] 
consciousness,  which  is  only  outbalanced  by  a  stronger 
consciousness.  This  occurs  in  all  cases  of  sensation,  and 
so  the  understanding  can  anticipate  even  sensations,  which 
constitute  the  peculiar  quality  of  empirical  representations 
(phenomena),  by  means  of  this  principle  :  that  they  all  have 
(consequently  that  what  is  real  in  all  phenomena  has)  a 
degree.  Here  [83]  is  the  second  application  of  Mathematic 
(mathesis  intensorum)  to  the  science  of  nature. 

§  25.  As  to  the  Relation  of  phenomena,  and  indeed 
merely  with  a  view  to  their  existence,  the  determination  is 
not  mathematical,  but  dynamical,  and  can  never  be  ob 
jectively  valid,  consequently  never  fit  for  experience,  if  it 
does  not  come  under  a  priori  principles  by  which  the 
cognition  of  experience  relative  to  phenomena  becomes  even 
possible.  Hence  phenomena  must  be  subsumed  under  the 
concept  of  Substance,  which  is  the  foundation  of  all  deter- 


83-84]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  65 

mination  of  existence,  as  a  concept  of  the  thing  itself;  or 
secondly — so  far  as  a  succession  is  found  among  pheno 
mena,  that  is,  an  event — under  the  concept  of  an  Effect 
with  reference  to  Cause ;  or  lastly — so  far  as  coexistence  is 
to  be  known  objectively,  that  is,  by  a  judgment  of  ex 
perience — under  the  concept  of  Community  (action  and 
reaction).  Thus  a  priori  principles  form  the  basis  of 
objectively  valid,  though  empirical  judgments,  that  is,  of  the 
possibility  of  experience  so  far  as  it  must  connect  objects 
as  existing  in  nature.  These  principles  are  the  proper  laws 
of  nature,  which  may  be  termed  dynamical. 

And  finally  the  cognition  of  the  agreement  and  connexion 
not  only  of  phenomena  among  themselves  in  experience, 
but  of  their  relation  to  experience  in  general,  belongs  to  the 
judgments  of  experience.  This  relation  [concerns]  either 
their  agreement  with  the  formal  conditions,  which  the 
understanding  [84]  cognises,  or  their  coherence  with  the 
materials  of  the  senses  and  of  perception,  or  combines  both 
into  one  concept.  Consequently  it  contains  Possibility, 
Actuality,  and  Necessity  according  to  universal  laws  of 
nature ;  and  this  constitutes  the  physiological  doctrine  of 
method,  or  the  distinction  of  truth  and  of  hypotheses,  and 
the  bounds  of  the  certainty  of  the  latter. 

§  26.  Yet  it  is  not  by  any  means  the  greatest  merit  of 
this  third  table  of  Principles  drawn  from  the  nature  of  the 
understanding  itself  after  the  critical  method,  that  it  shows 
an  inherent  perfection,  which  raises  it  far  above  every  other, 
that  has  hitherto  though  in  vain  been  tried  or  may  yet  be 
tried  by  analysing  things  themselves  dogmatically.  Nor  is  it 
[the  chief  merit]  that  the  table  exhibits  all  synthetical  a 
Priori  principles  completely  and  on  one  principle,  viz.  the 
faculty  of  judging  in  general,  which  constitutes  the  essence 
of  experience  as  regards  the  understanding,  so  that  we  can 

II  F 


66  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [84-85 

be  certain  that  there  are  no  more  such  like  principles — a 
satisfaction  which  the  dogmatical  method  never  can  afford. 

The  ground  of  proof  must  be  carefully  noticed,  as  it 
shows  the  possibility  of  this  cognition  a  priori,  and  at  the 
same  time  limits  all  such  principles  to  a  condition,  which 
must  never  be  forgotten,  if  we  desire  them  not  to  be  mis 
understood,  and  extended  in  use  beyond  the  original  sense 
which  the  under-  [85]  standing  attaches  to  them.  This 
limit  is,  that  they  contain  nothing  but  the  conditions  of 
possible  experience  in  general  so  far  as  it  is  subjected  to 
laws  a  priori.  Consequently  I  do  not  say,  that  things  in 
themselves  possess  a  quantity,  [that]  their  reality  [has]  a 
degree,  their  existence  a  connexion  of  accidents  in  a 
substance,  etc.  ;  for  this  nobody  can  prove,  because  such  a 
synthetical  connexion  from  mere  concepts,  without  any 
reference  to  sensuous  intuition  on  the  one  side,  or  con 
nexion  of  it  in  a  possible  experience  on  the  other,  is 
absolutely  impossible.  The  essential  limitation  of  the 
concepts  in  these  principles  then  is  :  That  all  things  stand 
necessarily  a  priori  under  the  afore -mentioned  conditions, 
as  objects  of  experience  only. 

Hence  there  follows  secondly  a  specifically  peculiar 
mode  of  proof  of  these  principles :  That  they  are  not 
referred  directly  to  phenomena  and  their  relation,  but  to 
the  possibility  of  experience,  of  which  phenomena  constitute 
the  matter  only,  not  the  form.  Thus  they  are  referred  to 
objectively  and  universally  valid  synthetical  propositions,  in 
which  [features]  judgments  of  experience  are  distinguished 
from  those  of  perception.  This  takes  place  because  pheno 
mena,  as  mere  intuitions,  which  occupy  a  part  of  space  and 
time,  come  under  the  concept  of  Quantity,  which  unites 
their  multiplicity  a  priori  according  to  rules  synthetically. 
Again,  so  far  as  the  perception  contains,  besides  intuition, 


86-87]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  67 

sensation,  between  which  [86]  and  nothing,  or  its  total 
disappearance,  a  transition  by  diminishing  always  occurs, 
what  is  real  in  phenomena  must  have  a  Degree,  so  far 
as  it  does  not  itself  occupy  any  part  of  space  or  of  time.1 
Still  the  transition  to  it  from  empty  time  or  space  is  only 
possible  in  time;  consequently  though  sensation,  as  the 
quality  of  empirical  intuition,  can  never  be  cognised  a  priori, 
by  its  specific  difference  from  other  sensations,  yet  it  can, 
in  a  possible  experience  in  general,  as  a  quantity  of  percep 
tion  be  intensively  distinguished  from  every  other  similar 
perception.  Hence  then  the  application  of  Mathematic  to 
nature  is  rendered  possible  and  determined,  as  regards  the 
sensuous  intuition  by  which  nature  is  given  to  us. 

But  the  reader  must  above  all  pay  attention  to  the  mode 
of  proof  of  the  principles  which  occur  under  the  title  of 
Analogies  of  experience.  For  [87]  these  do  not  regard  the 
generation  of  intuitions,  like  the  principles  of  the  application 
of  mathematic  to  the  science  of  nature  generally,  but  regard 
the  connexion  of  their  existence  in  experience.  This 
[connexion]  can  be  nothing  but  the  determination  of  their 
existence  in  time  according  to  necessary  laws,  under  which 
alone  the  connexion  is  objectively  valid,  and  consequently 
becomes  experience.  The  proof  therefore  does  not  turn  on 

1  Heat  and  light  are  in  a  small  space  just  as  large  (as  to  degree)  as 
in  a  large  one ;  in  like  manner  the  internal  representations,  pain, 
consciousness  in  general,  whether  they  last  a  short  or  a  long  time,  need 
not  vary  as  to  the  degree.  Hence  the  quantity  is  here  in  a  point  and 
in  a  moment  just  as  great  as  in  any  space  or  time  however  great. 
Degrees  are  therefore  capable  of  increase,  but  not  in  intuition,  rather  in 
mere  sensation  (or  the  quantity  of  the  degree  of  an  intuition).  Hence 
they  can  only  be  estimated  quantitatively  by  the  relation  of  I  to  o — that 
is,  by  their  capability  of  decreasing  by  infinite  intermediate  degrees  to 
disappearance,  or  of  increasing  from  nought  through  infinite  gradations 
to  a  determinate  sensation  in  a  certain  time.  Qtiantitas  qualitatis  est 
gradus. 


<>S  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [87-88 

the  synthetical  unity  in  the  connexion  of  things  in  them 
selves,  but  of  perceptions,  and  of  these  not  in  regard  to  their 
matter,  but  to  the  determination  of  time  and  of  the  relation 
of  their  existence  in  it,  according  to  universal  laws.  These 
universal  laws,  therefore,  if  the  empirical  determination  in 
relative  time  is  to  be  objectively  valid  (i.e.  to  be  experience), 
contain  the  necessary  determination  of  existence  in  time 
generally  (consequently  according  to  a  rule  of  the  under 
standing  a  priori].  The  reader  has  probably  been  long 
accustomed  to  consider  experience  a  mere  empirical  syn 
thesis  of  perceptions,  and  hence  not  to  reflect  that  it  goes 
much  farther  than  these  extend,  as  it  gives  empirical 
judgments  universal  validity,  and  for  that  purpose  requires 
a  pure  unity  of  the  understanding,  which  precedes  a  priori. 
In  Prolegomena  on  this  subject  I  can  only  recommend 
such  readers  to  pay  great  attention  to  this  distinction  of 
experience  from  a  mere  aggregate  of  perceptions,  and  to 
judge  the  mode  of  proof  from  this  point  of  view. 

[88]  §  27.  This  is  the  proper  place  to  remove  Hume's 
difficulty.  He  justly  maintains,  that  we  can  by  no  means 
see  by  reason  the  possibility  of  Causality,  that  is,  of  the  refer 
ence  of  the  existence  of  one  thing  to  the  existence  of  another, 
which  is  necessitated  by  the  former.  I  add,  that  we  com 
prehend  just  as  little  the  concept  of  Subsistence,  that  is,  the 
necessity  that  at  the  foundation  of  the  existence  of  things 
there  lies  a  subject  which  cannot  itself  be  a  predicate  of  any 
other  thing ;  nay,  we  cannot  even  form  a  notion  of  the 
possibility  of  such  a  thing  (though  we  can  point  out  examples 
of  its  use  in  experience).  The  very  same  incomprehensibility 
affects  the  Community  of  things,  as  we  cannot  comprehend 
how  from  the  state  of  one  thing  an  inference  to  the  state  of 
quite  another  thing  beyond  it,  and  vice  versa,  can  be  drawn, 
and  how  substances  which  have  each  their  own  separate 


88-89]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  69 

existence  should  depend  upon  one  another  necessarily. 
But  I  am  very  far  from  holding  these  concepts  to  be  derived 
merely  from  experience,  and  the  necessity  represented  in 
them,  to  be  imaginary  and  a  mere  illusion  produced  in  us  by 
long  habit.  On  the  contrary,  I  have  amply  shown,  that  they 
and  the  principles  [derived]  from  them  are  firmly  established 
a  priori,  or  before  all  experience,  and  have  their  undoubted 
objective  value,  though  only  with  regard  to  experience. 

§  28.  I  have  indeed  no  notion  of  such  a  connexion  of 
things  in  themselves,  that  they  can  either  [89]  exist  as  sub 
stances,  or  act  as  causes,  or  stand  in  community  with  others 
(as  parts  of  a  real  whole),  and  I  can  just  as  little  conceive 
such  properties  in  phenomena  as  such,  because  those  con 
cepts  contain  nothing  that  lies  in  the  phenomena,  but  what 
the  understanding  alone  must  think.  But  we  have  a  con 
cept  of  such  a  connexion  of  representations  in  our  under 
standing,  and  in  judgments  generally — a  concept  that 
representations  appear  in  one  sort  of  judgments  as  subject 
in  relation  to  predicate,  in  another  as  reason  in  relation 
to  consequence,  and  in  a  third  as  parts,  which  constitute 
together  a  total  possible  cognition.  Besides  we  cognise 
a  priori  that  without  considering  the  representation  of 
an  object  as  determined  in  some  of  these  respects,  we  can 
have  no  valid  cognition  of  the  object,  and,  if  we  should 
occupy  ourselves  about  the  object  per  se,  there  is  no  possible 
attribute,  by  which  I  could  know  that  it  is  determined  under 
any  of  these  aspects,  that  is,  under  the  concept  either  of  sub 
stance,  or  of  cause,  or  (in  relation  to  other  substances)  of 
community,  for  I  have  no  notion  of  the  possibility  of  such  a 
connexion  of  existence  \_per  se\.  But  the  question  is  not 
how  things  in  themselves,  but  how  the  empirical  cognition 
of  things  is  determined,  as  regards  the  above  aspects  of 
judgments  in  general,  that  is,  how  things,  as  objects  of  ex- 


70  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [89-91 

perience,  can  and  shall  be  subsumed  under  these  concepts 
of  the  understanding.  And  then  it  is  clear,  that  I  com 
pletely  comprehend  not  only  the  [90]  possibility,  but  also 
the  necessity  of  subsuming  all  phenomena  under  these 
concepts,  that  is,  of  using  them  for  principles  of  the  possi 
bility  of  experience. 

§  29.  Let  us  make  an  experiment  with  Hume's  prob 
lematical  concept  (his  crux  metaphysicorum}^  the  concept  of 
cause.  In  the  first  place  I  am  given  a  prior 7",  by  means  of 
logic,  the  form  of  a  conditional  judgment  in  general,  that  is, 
one  given  cognition  as  antecedent  and  another  as  consequent. 
But  it  is  possible,  that  in  perception  we  may  meet  with  a 
rule  of  relation,  which  runs  thus  :  that  a  certain  phenomenon 
is  constantly  followed  by  another  (though  not  conversely), 
and  this  is  a  case  for  me  to  use  the  hypothetical  judgment, 
and,  for  instance,  to  say,  if  the  sun  shines  long  enough  upon 
a  body,  it  grows  warm.  Here  there  is  indeed  as  yet  no 
necessity  of  connexion,  or  concept  of  cause.  But  I  proceed 
and  say,  that  if  the  [above]  proposition,  which  is  merely  a 
subjective  connexion  of  perceptions,  is  to  be  a  judgment  of 
experience,  it  must  be  considered  as  necessary  and  univer 
sally  valid.  Such  a  proposition  would  be,  '  the  sun  is  by  its 
light  the  cause  of  heat.'  The  empirical  rule  is  now  con 
sidered  as  a  law,  and  as  valid  not  merely  of  phenomena, 
but  valid  of  them  for  the  purposes  of  a  possible  experience 
which  requires  thoroughly  and  therefore  necessarily  valid 
rules.  I  therefore  easily  comprehend  the  concept  of  cause, 
as  a  concept  necessarily  belonging  to  the  mere  form  of  ex 
perience,  [91]  and  its  possibility  as  a  synthetical  union  of 
perceptions  in  consciousness  generally ;  but  I  do  not  at  all 
comprehend  the  possibility  of  a  thing  generally  as  a  cause, 
because  the  concept  of  cause  denotes  a  condition  not  at  all 
belonging  to  things,  but  to  experience.  It  is  nothing  in 


91-92]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  71 

fact  but  an  objectively  valid  cognition  of  phenomena  and  of 
their  succession,  so  far  as  the  antecedent  can  be  conjoined 
with  the  consequent  according  to  the  rule  of  hypothetical 
judgments. 

§  30.  Hence  to  the  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding^ 
if  they  quit  objects  of  experience  and  would  refer  to  things! 
in  themselves,  (noumena)  have  no  signification  whatever! 
They  serve,  as  it  were,  only  to  spell  phenomena,  that  we 
may  be  able  to  read  them  as  experience;  the  principles 
which  arise  from  their  reference  to  the  sensible  world,  only 
serve  our  understanding  for  empirical  use...  Beyond  this 
they  are  arbitrary  combinations,  without  objective  reality, 
and  we  can  neither  cognise  their  possibility  a  priori,  nor 
verify  their  reference  to  objects  or  make  it  intelligible  by 
any  example  ;  because  examples  can  only  be  borrowed  from 
some  possible  experience,  consequently  the  objects  of  these 
concepts  can  be  found  nowhere  but  in  a  possible  experience. 

This  complete  (though  to  its  originator  unexpected) 
solution  of  Hume's  problem  preserves  therefore  to  the  pure 
concepts  of  the  understanding  their  [92]  a  priori  origin,  and 
to  the  universal  laws  of  nature  their  validity,  as  laws  of  the 
understanding,  yet  so  that  their  use  is  limited  to  experience, 
because  their  possibility  depends  solely  on  the  reference  of 
the  understanding  to  experience ;  but  not  by  deriving  them 
from  experience,  but  by  deriving  it  from  them,  a  completely 
reversed  mode  of  connexion  which  never  occurred  to  Hume. 

This  is  therefore  the  result  of  all  our  foregoing  inquiries  : 
all  synthetical  principles  a  priori  are  nothing  more  than 
principles  of  possible  experience,  and  can  never  be  referred 
to  things  in  themselves,  but  to  phenomena  as  objects  of  ex 
perience.  And  hence  pure  mathematic  as  well  as  pure 
physic  can  never  be  referred  to  anything  more  than  mere 
phenomena,  and  can  only  represent  either  that  which  makes 


72  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [92-93 

experience  generally  possible,  or  else  that  which,  as  it  is 
derived  from  these  principles,  must  always  be  capable  of 
being  represented  in  some  possible  experience. 

§  31.  And  thus  we  have  at  last  something  definite,  upon 
which  to  depend  in  all  metaphysical  undertakings,  which 
have  hitherto  attempted  everything  without  distinction 
boldly  enough  but  always  at  random.  It  never  struck 
dogmatical  thinkers,  that  the  aim  of  their  exertions  should 
be  so  proximate.  It  never  struck  even  those,  who,  con 
fident  in  their  supposed  sound  common  sense,  started  with 
concepts  and  principles  of  pure  reason  (which  were  [93] 
legitimate  and  natural,  but  destined  for  mere  empirical  use) 
in  quest  of  fields  of  knowledge  \Einsichten\,  to  which  they 
neither  knew  nor  could  know  any  determinate  bounds, 
because  they  had  never  reflected  nor  were  able  to  reflect  on 
the  nature  or  even  on  the  possibility  of  such  a  pure  under 
standing. 

Many  a  naturalist  of  pure  reason  (by  which  I  mean  the 
man  who  believes  he  can  decide  in  matters  of  Metaphysic 
without  any  science)  may  pretend,  that  he  long  ago  by  the 
prophetic  spirit  of  his  sound  sense,  not  only  suspected,  but 
knew  and  comprehended,  what  is  here  propounded  with  so 
much  ado,  or,  if  he  likes,  with  prolix  and  pedantic  pomp : 
'  that  with  all  our  reason  we  can  never  reach  beyond  the 
field  of  experience.'  But  when  he  is  questioned  about  his 
rational  principles  individually,  he  must  grant,  that  there  are 
many  of  them  which  he  has  not  taken  from  experience,  and 
which  are  therefore  independent  of  it  and  valid  a  priori. 
How  then  and  on  what  grounds  will  he  restrain  both  him 
self  and  the  dogmatist,  who  makes  use  of  these  concepts 
and  principles  beyond  all  possible  experience,  because  they 
are  recognised  independent  of  it  ?  And  even  he,  this  adept 
in  sound  sense,  in  spite  of  all  the  cheaply  acquired  wisdom 


93-951  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  73 

he  arrogates  to  himself,  is  not  so  secure  from  [the  danger 
of]  wandering  insensibly  beyond  objects  of  experience  into 
the  field  of  chimeras.  He  too  is  often  deeply  enough  [94] 
involved  in  them,  though  he  gives  a  colour  to  his  groundless 
pretensions  by  his  popular  language,  in  which  he  announces 
everything  as  mere  probability,  rational  conjecture,  or 
analogy. 

§  32.  Since  the  oldest  days  of  philosophy  inquirers  into 
pure  reason  have  conceived,  besides  the  things  of  sense, 
or  appearances  (phenomena),  which  make  up  the  sensible 
world,  certain  objects  of  the  understanding1  (noumend), 
which  should  constitute  an  intelligible  world.  And  as 
appearance  and  illusion  were  by  those  men  identified  (a 
thing  which  we  may  well  excuse  in  an  undeveloped  epoch), 
actuality  was  only  conceded  to  the  noumena. 

And  we  indeed,  when,  as  is  reasonable,  we  consider 
objects  of  sense  as  mere  appearances,  hereby  confess  that 
they  are  based  upon  a  thing  in  itself,  though  we  know  not 
this  thing  as  to  its  internal  constitution,  but  only  know  its 
phenomena,  viz.  :  the  way  in  which  our  senses  are  affected 
by  this  unknown  something.  The  understanding  therefore, 
by  assuming  phenomena,  grants  the  existence  of  things  in 
themselves  also,  and  so  far  we  may  say,  that  the  repre 
sentation  of  such  beings  as  form  the  basis  of  phenomena, 
consequently  of  mere  beings  of  the  understanding,  is  not 
only  admissible,  but  unavoidable. 

Our  critical  deduction  by  no  means  excludes  [95]  beings 
of  that  sort  (noumena) ,  but  rather  limits  the  principles  of  the 
Aesthetic  to  this,  that  they  shall  not  extend  to  all  things,  as 
everything  would  then  be  turned  into  mere  phenomenon, 
but  that  they  shall  only  hold  good  of  objects  of  possible 
experience.  Hereby  then  objects  of  the  understanding  are 
1  Verstandeswesen ,  using  object  in  its  vaguest  sense.  M. 


74  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [95-96 

granted,  but  with  the  inculcation  of  this  rule  which  admits 
of  no  exception  :  '  that  we  neither  know  nor  can  know  any 
thing  at  all  determinate  of  these  pure  objects  of  the  under 
standing,  because  our  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding  as 
well  as  our  pure  intuitions  extend  to  nothing  but  objects  of 
possible  experience,  consequently  to  mere  things  of  sense, 
and  as  soon  as  we  leave  this  sphere  these  concepts  retain  no 
meaning  whatever.' 

§  33.  There  is  indeed  something  seductive  in  our  pure 
concepts  of  the  understanding,  which  tempts  us  to  a  tran 
scendent  use  ;  I  mean  the  use  which  transcends  all  possible 
experience.  Not  only  are  our  concepts  of  substance,  of 
power,  of  action,  of  reality,  and  others,  quite  independent 
of  experience,  containing  no  phenomenon  of  sense,  and  so 
apparently  applicable  to  things  in  themselves  (noumena), 
but,  what  strengthens  this  presumption,  they  contain  a 
necessity  of  determination  in  themselves,  which  experience 
never  attains.  The  concept  of  cause  implies  a  rule,  accord 
ing  to  which  one  state  follows  another  necessarily;  but 
experience  can  only  show  us,  that  one  state  of  things  often, 
or  at  most,  [96]  commonly,  follows  another,  and  therefore 
affords  neither  strict  universality,  nor  necessity. 

Hence  the  Categories  seem  to  have  a  deeper  meaning 
and  import  than  can  be  exhausted  by  their  empirical  use, 
and  so  the  understanding  insensibly  adds  for  itself  to  the 
house  of  experience  a  much  more  extensive  wing,  which  it 
fills,  with  nothing  but  creatures  of  thought,  without  ever 
observing  that  it  has  transgressed  with  its  otherwise  lawful 
concepts  the  bounds  of  their  use. 

§  34.  I  was  obliged  therefore  to  institute  two  important, 
and  even  indispensable,  though  very  dry  investigations.  In 
the  one  (Krttik,  p.  107)  it  is  shown,  that  the  senses  furnish 
not  the  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding  in  concrete,  but 


96-97]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE  ?  75 

only  the  schema  for  their  use,  and  that  the  object  conform 
able  to  it  occurs  only  in  experience  (as  the  production  of 
the  understanding  from  materials  of  the  sensibility).  In  the 
other  (Kritik)  p.  178)  it  is  shown,  that,  although  our  pure 
concepts  of  the  understanding  and  our  principles  are  inde 
pendent  of  experience,  and  despite  of  the  apparently  greater 
sphere  of  their  use,  still  nothing  whatever  can  be  thought 
by  them  beyond  the  field  of  experience,  because  they  can 
do  nothing  but  merely  determine  the  logical  form  of  the 
judgment  relatively  to  given  intuitions.  But  as  there  is  no 
intuition  at  all  beyond  the  field  of  the  sensibility,  these  pure 
concepts,  as  they  cannot  possibly  be  exhibited  in  concrete, 
are  [then]  totally  [97]  without  meaning;  consequently  all 
these  nonmena,  together  with  their  complex,  the  intelligible 
world,1  are  nothing  but  representation  of  a  problem,  of  which 
the  object  in  itself  is  possible,  but  the  solution,  from  the 
nature  of  our  understanding,  totally  impossible.  For  our 
understanding  is  not  a  faculty  of  intuition,  but  of  the  con 
nexion  of  given  intuitions  in  experience.  Experience  must 
therefore  contain  all  the  objects  for  our  concepts ;  but 
beyond  it  no  concepts  have  any  signification,  as  there  is  no 
intuition  for  their  basis. 

§  35.  The  imagination  may  perhaps  be  forgiven  for 
occasional  extravagance,  and  for  not  keeping  carefully  within 
the  limits  of  experience,  since  it  at  least  gains  life  and  vigour 

1  Not  (as  the  usual  expression  is)  intellectual  world.  For  cognitions 
are  intellectual  through  the  understanding,  and  refer  to  our  world  of 
sense  also  ;  but  objects,  so  far  as  they  can  be  represented  merely  by  the 
understanding^  and  to  which  none  of  our  sensible  intuitions  can  refer, 
are  termed  intelligible.  But  as  some  possible  intuition  must  correspond 
to  every  object,  we  must  conceive  an  understanding  that  intuites  things 
immediately  ;  but  of  such  we  have  not  the  least  notion,  nor  have  we  of 
the  things  of  understanding  [Verstandeswesen],  to  which  it  should  be 
applied. 


76  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [97-98 

by  such  flights,  and  since  it  is  always  easier  to  moderate  its 
boldness,  than  to  stimulate  its  languor.  But  the  under 
standing  which  ought  to  think  can  never  be  forgiven  for 
substituting  extravagance  ;  for  we  depend  upon  it  alone  for 
assistance  to  set  bounds,  when  necessary,  to  the  extrava 
gance  of  the  imagination. 

[98]  But  the  understanding  begins  its  vagaries  very 
innocently  and  modestly.  It  first  separates  the  elementary 
cognitions,  which  inhere  in  it  prior  to  all  experience,  but 
yet  must  always  have  their  application  in  experience.  It 
gradually  drops  these  limits,  and  what  is  there  to  prevent  it, 
as  it  has  quite  freely  derived  its  principles  from  itself?  And 
then  it  proceeds  first  to  newly-imagined  powers  in  nature, 
then  to  beings  outside  nature  ;  in  short  to  a  world,  for  whose 
construction  the  materials  cannot  be  wanting,  because  fertile 
fiction  furnishes  them  abundantly,  and  though  not  confirmed, 
is  never  refuted,  by  experience.  This  is  the  reason  that 
young  thinkers  are  so  partial  to  Metaphysic  of  the  truly 
dogmatical  kind,  and  often  sacrifice  to  it  their  time  and 
their  talents,  which  might  be  otherwise  better  employed. 

But  there  is  no  use  in  trying  to  moderate  these  fruitless 
endeavours  of  pure  reason  by  all  manner  of  cautions  as  to 
the  difficulties  of  solving  questions  so  occult,  by  complaints 
of  the  limits  of  our  reason,  and  by  degrading  our  assertions 
into  mere  conjectures.  For,  if  their  impossibility  is  not  dis 
tinctly  shown,  and  the  self-knowledge  of  reason  does  not 
become  a  true  science,  in  which  the  field  of  its  right  use  is 
distinguished,  so  to  say,  with  mathematical  certainty  from 
that  of  its  worthless  and  idle  use,  these  fruitless  efforts  will 
never  be  fully  abandoned. 


99-ioo]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  77 

[99]  §36-  How  is  Nature  itself  possible  1 

This  question — the  highest  point  that  transcendental 
philosophy  can  ever  reach,  and  to  which,  as  its  boundary 
and  completion,  it  must  proceed — properly  contains  two 
[subordinate]  questions. 

FIRST:  How  is  nature  at  all  possible  in  the  material 
sense,  as  to  intuition,  [I  mean  nature]  considered  as  the 
complex  of  phenomena ;  how  are  space,  time,  and  that  which 
fills  both — the  object  of  sensation,  in  general  possible  ? 
The  answer  is :  By  means  of  the  constitution  of  our 
Sensibility,  according  to  which  it  is  specifically  affected  by 
objecjs,  which  are  in  themselves  unknown  to  it,  and  totally 
distijicLJbwn  those  phenomena.  This  answer  is  given  in 
the  Kritik  itself  in  the  transcendental  Aesthetic,  and  in  these 
Prolegomena  by  the  solution  of  the  first  general  problem. 

SECONDLY  :  How  is  nature  possible  in  the  formal  sense, 
nature  as  the  complex  of  the  rules,  under  which  all  pheno 
mena  must  come,  in  order  to  be  thought  as  connected  in 
experience  ?  The  answer  must  be  this  :  It  is  only  possible 
by  means  of  the  constitution  of  our  Understanding,  according 
to  which  all  the  above  representations  of  the  sensibility  are 
necessarily  referred  to  a  consciousness,  and  by  which  the 
peculiar  way  in  which  we  think  (that  is,  by  rules),  and  hence 
experience  also,  are  possible,  but  must  be  clearly  distin 
guished  from  an  insight  [100]  into  the  objects  in  themselves. 
This  answer  is  given  in  the  Kritik  itself  in  the  transcend 
ental  Logic,  and  in  these  Prolegomena,  in  the  course  of  the 
solution  of  the  second  main  problem. 

But  how  this  peculiar  property  of  our  sensibility  itself  is 
possible,  or  that  of  our  understanding  and  of  the  appercep 
tion  which  is  necessarily  its  basis  and  that  of  all  thinking — 
this  cannot  be  further  resolved  or  answered,  because  we 


78  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [100-101 

require  these  [faculties]  for  all  our  answers  and  for  all  our 
thinking  about  objects. 

There  are  many  laws  of  nature,  which  we  can  only  know 
by  means  of  experience ;  but  conformity  to  law  in  the  con 
nexion  of  phenomena,  that  is,  nature  in  general,  we  cannot 
discover  by  any  experience,  because  experience  itself  requires 
laws,  which  are  a  priori  at  the  basis  of  its  possibility. 

The  possibility  of  experience  in  general  is  therefore  at 
the  same  time  the  universal  law  of  nature,  and  the  principles 
of  the  former  (experience)  are  the  very  laws  of  the  latter 
(nature).  For  we  do  not  know  nature  but  as  the  complex 
of  the  phenomena,  that  is,  of  representations  in  us,  and 
hence  can  only  jerive  the  laws  of  its  connexion  from  the 
r2rjnciples  of  thejr_connexion  in  us,  that  is,  from  the  condi 
tions  of  their  necessary  union  in  consciousness,  which  union 
constitutes  the  possibility  of  experience. 

Even  the  main  proposition  expounded  throughout  this 
section — that  universal  laws  of  nature  can  [101]  be  distinctly 
cognised  a  priori — leads  naturally  to  the  proposition  :  that 
the  highest  legislation  of  nature  must  lie  in  ourselves  (that  is, 
in  our  understanding),  and  that  we  must  not  seek  the  universal 
laws  of  nature  in  nature  by  means  of  experience,  but  con 
versely  must  seek  nature,  as  to  its  universal  conformity  to  law, 
in  the  conditions  of  the  possibility  of  experience,  which  lie  in 
our  sensibility  and  in  our  understanding.  For  how  were  it 
otherwise  possible  to  know  a  priori  these  laws,  as  they  are 
not  rules  of  analytical  cognition,  but  really  synthetical  exten 
sions  of  it  ?  Such  a  necessary  agreement  of  the  principles 
of  possible  experience  with  the  laws  of  the  possibility  of 
nature,  can  only  proceed  from  one  of  two  reasons  :  either 
these  laws  are  drawn  from  nature  by  means  of  experience, 
j  or  conversely  nature  is  derived  from  the  laws  of  the  possi 
bility  of  experience  in  general,  and  is  quite  the  same  as  the 


ioi-io2]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  79 

mere  universal  conformity  to  law  of  the  latter.  The  former 
is  self-contradictory,  for  the  universal  laws  of  nature  can  and 
must  be  cognised  a  priori  (that  is,  independent  of  all  experi 
ence),  and  be  the  foundation  of  all  empirical  use  of  the  under 
standing;  the  latter  alternative  therefore  alone  remains.1 

[102]  But  we  must  distinguish  the  empirical  laws  of 
nature,  which  always  presuppose  particular  perceptions,  from 
J±L£_pure  or  universal  laws  of  nature,  which,  without  being 
based  on  particular  perceptions,  contain  merely  the  condi 
tions  of  their  necessary  union  in  experience.  Iri_relation_to 
the  latter,  natiji^j.nd^££^expe£ience  are  quite  the_same. 
and  as  the  conformity  to  law  here  depends  upon  the 
necessary  connexion  of  phenomena  in  experience  (without 
which  we  cannot  cognise  any  object  whatever  in  the  sensible 
world),  consequently  upon  the  original  laws  of  the  under 
standing,  it  seems  at  first  strange,  but  is  not  the  less  certain, 
to  says  as  regards  the  latter :  The  understanding  does 
not  draw  its  laws  (a  priori]  from  nature,  but  prescribes  them 
to  it 

§  37.  We  shall  illustrate  this  apparently  daring  proposi 
tion  by  an  example,  which  will  show,  that  laws,  which  we 
discover  in  objects  of  sensuous  intuition  (especially  when 
these  laws  are  cognised  as  necessary),  are  commonly  held 
by  us  to  be  such  as  the  understanding  has  placed  in  them, 
though  they  are  similar  in  all  points  to  the  laws  of  nature, 
which  we  ascribe  to  experience. 

1  Crusius  alone  thought  of  a  compromise  :  that  a  Spirit,  who  can 
neither  err  nor  deceive,  implanted  these  laws  in  us  originally.  But 
since  false  principles  often  intrude  themselves,  as  indeed  the  very 
system  of  this  man  shows  in  not  a  few  examples,  we  are  involved  in 
difficulties  as  to  the  use  of  such  a  principle  in  the  absence  of  sure 
criteria  to  distinguish  the  genuine  origin  from  the  spurious,  as  we  never 
can  know  certainly  what  the  Spirit  of  truth  or  the  father  of  lies  may  have 
instilled  into  us. 


8o  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [102-104 

§  38.  If  we  consider  the  properties  of  the  circle,  by  [103] 
which  this  figure  unites  so  many  arbitrary  determinations 
of  space  in  itself,  and  therefore  in  a  universal  rule,  we  can 
not  avoid  attributing  a  nature  to  this  geometrical  thing. 
Two  right  lines,  for  example,  which  intersect  one  another 
and  the  circle,  however  they  may  be  drawn,  are  always 
divided  so  that  the  rectangle  under  the  segments  of  the  one 
is  equal  to  that  under  the  segments  of  the  other.  The 
question  now  is  :  Does  this  law  lie  in  the  circle  or  in  the 
understanding,  that  is,  Does  this  figure,  independently  of 
the  understanding,  contain  in  itself  the  ground  of  the  law, 
or  does  the  understanding,  having  constructed  according  to 
its  concepts  (according  to  the  equality  of  the  radii)  the  figure 
itself,  introduce  into  it  this  law  of  the  chords  cutting  one 
another  in  geometrical  proportion  ?  When  we  follow  the 
proofs  of  this  law,  we  soon  perceive,  that  it  can  only  be  de 
rived  from  the  condition  on  which  the  understanding  founds 
the  construction  of  this  figure,  and  which  is  that  of  the 
equality  of  the  radii.  But,  if  we  enlarge  this  concept,  to 
pursue  further  the  unity  of  various  properties  of  geometrical 
figures  under  common  laws,  and  consider  the  circle  as  a 
conic  section,  which  of  course  is  subject  to  the  same  funda 
mental  conditions  of  construction  as  other  conic  sections, 
we  shall  find,  that  all  the  chords,  which  intersect  within  the 
ellipse,  parabola,  and  hyperbola,  always  intersect  so  that  the 
rectangles  under  their  segments  are  not  indeed  equal,  [104] 
but  always  bear  a  constant  ratio  to  one  another  [the 
directions  of  the  chords  being  fixed].  If  we  proceed  still 
farther,  to  the  fundamental  laws  of  physical  astronomy,  we 
find  a  physical  law  of  reciprocal  attraction  diffused  over  all 
material  nature,  the  rule  of  which  attraction  is  :  '  that  it 
decreases  inversely  as  the  square  of  the  distance  from  each 
attracting  point,  that  is,  as  the  spherical  surfaces,  over  which 


104-105]  HOW  IS  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  81 

this  power  diffuses  itself — increase,'  which  law  seems  to  be 
necessarily  inherent  in  the  very  nature  of  things,  and  hence 
is  usually  propounded  as  cognisable  a  priori.  Simple  as 
the  sources  of  this  law  are,  merely  resting  upon  the  relation 
of  spherical  surfaces  of  different  radii,  its  consequences  are 
so  valuable  with  regard  to  the  variety  of  their  agreement  and 
its  regularity,  that  not  only  are  all  possible  orbits  of  the 
celestial  bodies  conic  sections,  but  such  a  relation  of  these 
orbits  to  each  other  results,  that  no  other  law  of  attraction, 
than  that  of  the  inverse  square  of  the  distance,  can  be 
imagined  as  fit  for  a  cosmical  system. 

Here  then  is  a  Nature  that  rests  upon  laws  which  the 
understanding  cognises  a  priori,  and  chiefly  from  the 
universal  principles  of  the  determination  of  space.  And  the 
question  now  is  :  Do  the  laws  of  nature  lie  in  space,  and 
does  the  understanding  learn  them  by  merely  endeavouring 
to  find  out  the  fruitful  meaning  that  lies  in  space ;  or  do 
they  [105]  inhere  in  the  understanding  and  in  the  way  in 
which  it  determines  space  according  to  the  conditions  of  the 
synthetical  unity  in  which  its  concepts  are  all  centred? 
Space  is  something  so  uniform  and  as  to  all  particular 
properties  so  indeterminate,  that  we  should  certainly  not 
seek  a  store  of  laws  of  nature  in  it.  Whereas  that  which 
determines  space  to  the  form  of  a  circle  or  to  the  figures  of, 
a  cone  and  a  sphere,  is  the  understanding,  so  far  as  it 
contains  the  ground  of  the  unity  of  their  constructions. 
The  mere  universal  form  of  intuition,  called  space,  must 
therefore  be  the  substratum  of  all  intuitions  determinable  to 
particular  objects,  and  in  it  of  course  the  condition  of  the 
possibility  and  of  the  variety  of  these  intuitions  lies.  But 
the  unity  of  the  objects  is  entirely  determined  by  the  under 
standing,  and  on  conditions  which  lie  in  its  own  nature  ;  and 
thus  the  understanding  js  the  origin  nf  the  universal  order 
II  G 


82  PROLEGOMENA  TO   METAPHYSIC          [105-106 

pi-iiatiire+JUi  that  it  compreb.ends_a]JLjj)pearances  underjts 
wSj  nrd  thereby  first  constructs,  a  priori*  experience 


(as  to  its  form),  by  means  of  which  whatever  is  to  be  cog 
nised  only  by  experience,  is  subjected  to  its  laws  necessarily. 
For  we  are  not  now  concerned  with  the  nature  of  things  in 
themselves,  which  is  independent  of  the  conditions  both  of 
our  sensibility  and  our  understanding,  but  with  nature,  as 
an.j)bj(ect^L-pos8ible  experience,  and  [106]  in~tRTs~caselhe 
understanding,  whilst  it  makes  experience  possible,  thereby 
insists  that  the  sensuous  world  is  either  not  an  object  of 
experience  at  all,  or  must  be  Nature. 


APPENDIX  TO  THE  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE 

§  39.   Of  the  System  of  the  Categories 

THERE  can  be  nothing  more  desirable  to  a  philosopher, 
than  to  be  able  to  derive  the  scattered  multiplicity  of  the 
concepts  or  the  principles,  which  had  occurred  to  him  in 
concrete  use,  from  a  principle  a  priori,  and  to  unite  every 
thing  in  this  way  in  one  cognition.  He  formerly  only 
believed  that  those  things,  which  remained  after  a  certain 
abstraction,  and  seemed  by  comparison  among  one  another 
to  constitute  a  particular  kind  of  cognitions,  were  completely 
collected ;  but  this  was  only  an  Aggregate.  Now  he 
knows,  that  just  so  many,  neither  more  nor  less,  can  consti 
tute  the  mode  of  cognition,  and  perceives  the  necessity  of 
his  division,  which  is  a  [mental]  comprehension ;  and  now 
only  he  has  attained  a  System. 

To  search  in  common  cognition  for  the  concepts,  which 
do  not  rest  upon  particular  experience,  and  yet  occur  in  all 
cognition  of  experience,  [107]  in  which  they  as  it  were  consti 
tute  the  mere  form  of  connexion — to  do  this  presupposes 
neither  greater  reflection  nor  deeper  insight,  than  to  detect  in 
a  language  the  rules  of  the  actual  use  of  words  generally,  and 
thus  to  collect  elements  for  a  grammar.  In  fact  both 
researches  are  very  nearly  related,  even  though  we  are  not 
able  to  give  a  reason  why  each  language  has  just  this  and 


84  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [107-108 

no  other  formal  constitution,  and  still  less  why  an  exact 
number  of  such  formal  determinations  in  general  are  found 
in  it. 

Aristotle  collected  ten  pure  elementary  concepts  under 
the  name  of  Categories.1  To  these,  which  are  also  called  pre 
dicaments,  he  found  himself  obliged  afterwards  to  add  five 
post-predicaments,2  some  of  which  however  (prius,  simul^ 
and  motus}  are  contained  in  the  former ;  but  this  random 
collection  must  rather  be  considered  (and  commended)  as 
a  hint  for  future  inquirers,  than  as  a  regularly  developed 
idea,  and  hence  it  has,  in  the  present  more  advanced 
state  of  philosophy,  been  rejected  as  quite  useless. 

After  long  reflection  on  the  pure  elements  of  human 
knowledge  (those  which  contain  nothing  empirical),  I  at 
last  succeeded  in  distinguishing  [108]  with  certainty  and  in 
separating  the  pure  elementary  notions  of  the  Sensibility  (space 
and  time)  from  those  of  the  Understanding.  Thus  the  yth, 
8th,  and  Qth  Categories  are  excluded  from  the  old  list. 
And  the  others  were  of  no  service  to  me ;  because  there 
was  [in  Aristotle's  mind]  no  principle,  on  which  the  under 
standing  could  be  fully  investigated,  and  all  the  functions, 
whence  its  pure  concepts  arise,  determined  completely  and 
with  precision. 

But  in  order  to  discover  such  a  principle,  I  looked  about 
for  an  act  of  theoindezstanding  which  rnrnprjsf s  all  fh**  rp^ 
and  is  distinguished  only  by  various  modifications  or 
phases,  in  reducing  the  multiplicity  of  representation  to 
the  unity  of  thinking  in  general :  I  found  this  act  of  the 
understanding  to  consist  in  judging.  Here  then  the  labours 
of  the  logicians  were  ready  at  hand,  though  not  yet  quite 

1  i.  Substantia.     2.  Qualitas.     3.  Quantitas.     4.  Relatio.     5.  Adio. 
6.  Passt'o.     7.  Quando.     8.  Ubi.     9.  Situs.     10.  Habitus. 

2  Oppositum.     Prius.     Simiil.     Motus.     Habere. 


108-109]    OF  THE  SYSTEM  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  85 

free  from  defects,  and  with  this  help  I  was  enabled  to 
exhibit  a  complete  table  of  the  pure  functions  of  the  under 
standing,  which  are  however  undetermined  in  regard  to  any 
object.  I  finally  referred  these  functions  of  judging  to 
objects  in  general,  or  rather  to  the  condition  oLd 
iudgments_as_pbjectively  valid,  and  so  there  arose 
concepts  of  t.h&  understanding,  concerning  which  I  could 
make  certain,  that  these,  and  this  exact  number  only,  con 
stitute  our  whole  cognition  of  things  from  pure  under 
standing.  I  was  justi- [109]  fied  in  calling  them  by  their 
old  name,  Categories ;  while  I  reserved  for  myself  the 
liberty  of  adding,  under  the  title  of  Predicables^  a  complete 
list  of  all  the  concepts  deducible  from  them,  by  combinations 
whether  among  themselves,  or  with  the  pure  form  of  the 
phenomenon  (space  or  time),  or  with  its  matter,  so  far  as  it 
is  not  yet  empirically  determined  (the  object  of  sensation 
in  general).  This  should  be  done  as  soon  as  a  system  of 
transcendental  philosophy,  towards  which  I  am  at  present 
only  contributing  by  the  Kritik  of  the  Reason  itself,  comes 
to  be  constructed. 

Now  the  essential  point  in  this  system  of  Categories, 
which  distinguishes  it  from  the  old  random  collection 
without  principle,  and  for  which  alone  it  deserves  to  be 
considered  as  philosophy,  consists  in  this  :  that  by  means 
of  it  the  true  signification  of  the  pure  concepts  of  the 
understanding  and  the  condition  of  their  use  could  be  pre 
cisely  determined.  For  here  it  became  obvious  that  they 
are  themselves  nothing  but  logical  functions,  and  as  such 
do  not  produce  the  least  concept  of  an  object,  but  require 
sensuous  intuition  as  a  basis.  They  therefore  only  serve  to 
determine  empirical  judgments,  which  are  otherwise  un 
determined  and  indifferent  as  regards  all  functions  of 
judging,  relatively  to  these  functions,  thereby  procuring 


86  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [109-111 

them  universal  validity,   and   by  means   of  them  making 
judgments  of  experience  in  general  possible. 

[no]  Such  an  insight  into  the  nature  of  the  categories, 
which  limits  them  at  the  same  time  to  the  mere  use  of 
experience,  never  occurred  either  to  their  first  author,  or  to 
any  of  his  successors;  but  without  this  insight  (which 
immediately  depends  upon  their  derivation  or  deduction), 
they  are  quite  useless  and  only  a  miserable  list  of  names, 
without  explanation  or  rule  for  their  use.  Had  the  ancients 
ever  conceived  such  a  notion,  doubtless  the  whole  study  of 
the  pure  rational  knowledge,  which  under  the  name  of 
Metaphysic  has  for  centuries  spoiled  many  a  sound  mind, 
would  have  reached  us  in  quite  another  shape,  and  would 
have  enlightened  the  human  understanding,  instead  of 
actually  exhausting  it  in  obscure  and  vain  subtilties,  and 
rendering  it  unfit  for  true  science. 

Again  :  this  system  of  categories  makes  all  treatment 
of  every  object  of  pure  reason  itself  systematic,  and  affords 
a  direction  or  clue  how  and  through  what  points  of 
inquiry  every  metaphysical  consideration  must  proceed,  in 
order  to  be  complete ;  for  it  exhausts  all  the  momenta  of 
the  understanding,  among  which  every  concept  must  be 
classed.  In  like  manner  the  table  of  Principles  found  its 
origin,  the  completeness  of  which  we  can  only  vouch  for  by 
the  system  of  the  categories ;  and  even  in  the  division  of 
the  concepts,1  which  must  go  [i  1 1]  beyond  the  physiological 
use  of  the  understanding,  it  is  the  very  same  clue,  which,  as 
it  must  always  be  carried  through  the  same  fixed  points 
determined  a  priori  in  the  human  understanding,  always 
forms  a  closed  circle ;  so  that  there  is  no  doubt  that  the 
object  of  a  pure  understanding  or  of  a  rational-concept,  so 
far  as  it  is  to  be  estimated  philosophically  and  on  a  priori 
1  Kritik,  pp.  207  and  257. 


1 1I-U2]    OF  THE  SYSTEM  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  87 

principles,  can  in  this  way  be  completely  cognised.  I  could 
not  therefore  omit  to  make  use  of  this  clue  with  regard  to 
one  of  the  most  abstract  ontological  divisions,  the  various 
distinctions  of  the  notions  of  something  and  of  nothing,  and 
to  construct  accordingly  (Kritik,  p.  207)  a  regular  and 
necessary  table  of  their  divisions.1 

[112]  And  this  system,  like  every  other  true  one  founded 
on  a  universal  principle,  shows  its  inestimable  value  in  this, 
that  it  excludes  all  foreign  concepts,  which  might  otherwise 
intrude  among  the  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding,  and 
determines  the  place  of  every  cognition.  Those  concepts, 
which  under  the  name  of  concepts  of  reflection  have  been 
likewise  arranged  in  a  table,  according  to  the  clue  of  the 
categories,  intrude  themselves,  without  leave  or  right,  among 
the  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding  in  Ontology,  though 
these  are  concepts  of  connexion,  and  thereby  of  the  objects 
themselves,  whereas  the  former  are  only  concepts  of  the 

1  Many  neat  observations  may  be  made  on  the  table  of  the  categories, 
for  instance  :  (i)  that  the  third  arises  from  the  first  and  the  second 
joined  in  one  concept ;  (2)  that  in  those  of  Quantity  and  of  Quality 
there  is  merely  a  progress  from  unity  to  totality  or  from  something  to 
nothing  (for  this  purpose  the  categories  of  Quality  must  stand  thus  : 
reality,  limitation,  total  negation),  without  correlata  or  opposita^  whereas 
those  of  Relation  and  of  Modality  carry  such  with  them  ;  (3)  that,  as  in 
Logic  categorical  judgments  are  the  basis  of  all  others,  so  the  category  of 
Substance  is  the  basis  of  all  concepts  of  actual  things ;  (4)  that  as 
Modality  in  the  judgment  is  not  a  particular  predicate,  so  by  the  modal 
concepts  a  determination  is  not  superadded  to  things,  etc.  etc.  Such 
observations  are  of  great  use.  If  we  besides  enumerate  all  the  predic- 
ables,  which  we  can  find  pretty  completely  in  any  good  ontology  (for 
example,  Baumgarten's),  and  arrange  them  in  classes  under  the  categories, 
in  which  operation  we  must  not  neglect  to  add  as  complete  a  dissection 
of  all  these  concepts  as  possible,  there  will  then  arise  a  merely 
analytical  part  of  Metaphysic,  which  does  not  contain  a  single  synthetical 
proposition,  which  might  precede  the  second  (the  synthetical),  and  would 
by  its  precision  and  completeness  be  not  only  useful,  but,  in  virtue  of 
its  system,  be  even  to  some  extent  elegant. 


SS  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [112-113 

mere  comparison  of  concepts  already  given,  and  are  hence 
of  quite  another  nature  and  use ;  by  my  orderly  division  x 
they  are  saved  from  this  confusion.  But  the  value  of  my 
separate  table  of  the  categories  will  be  still  more  obvious, 
when  we  presently  separate  the  table  of  the  transcendental 
concepts  of  Reason,  which  are  of  quite  another  nature  and 
[113]  origin,  and  hence  must  have  quite  another  form  from 
the  concepts  of  the  understanding.  This  so  necessary 
separation  has  never  yet  been  made  in  any  system  of 
Metaphysic  [where  on  the  contrary]  these  rational  Ideas 
live  with  the  categories  without  separation,  like  the  children 
of  one  family — a  confusion  not  to  be  avoided  in  the  absence 
of  a  definite  system  of  categories. 

1  Kritik,  p.  190  sqq. 


[n4]  THIRD  PART  OF  THE  MAIN  TRAN 
SCENDENTAL   PROBLEM 

How  is  Metaphysic  in  General  Possible  ? 

§40.  PURE  Mathematic  and  pure  Science  of  Nature  had 
no  occasion  for  such  a  deduction,  as  we  have  made  of  both, 
for  their  own  safety  and  certainty;  for  the  former  rests  upon 
its  own  evidence ;  and  the  latter  (though  sprung  from  pure 
sources  of  the  understanding)  upon  experience  and  its 
thorough  confirmation,  which  latter  testimony  Physic  can 
not  altogether  refuse  and  dispense  with ;  because  with  all 
its  certainty,  it  can  never,  as  philosophy,  rival  Mathematic. 
Both  sciences  therefore  stood  in  need  of  this  inquiry,  not 
for  themselves,  but  for  the  sake  of  another  science,  Meta 
physic. 

Metaphysic  has  to  do  not  only  with  concepts  of  nature, 
which  always  find  their  application  in  experience,  but  with 
pure  rational  Concepts,  which  never  can  be  given  in  any 
possible  experience,  consequently  with  concepts  whose 
objective  reality  (as  different  from  mere  chimeras),  and 
with  assertions  whose  truth  or  falsity,  cannot  be  discovered 
or  confirmed  by  any  experience.  This  part  of  Metaphysic 
[115]  is  precisely  what  constitutes  its  essential  end,  to 
which  the  rest  is  only  a  means,  and  thus  this  science 
requires  a  similar  deduction  for  its  own  sake.  The  third 


90  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC         [115-116 

question  now  proposed  relates  therefore  as  it  were  to  the 
root  and  essential  difference  of  Metaphysic,  that  is,  the 
occupation  of  Reason  with  itself,  and  the  supposed 
knowledge  of  objects  arising  immediately  from  this  incuba 
tion  of  its  own  concepts,  without  requiring,  or  indeed  being 
able  to  reach  that  knowledge  through,  experience.1 

Without  resolving  this  question  reason  never  does  itself 
justice.  The  empirical  use  to  which  reason  limits  the  pure 
understanding,  does  not  satisfy  its  proper  destination. 
Every  single  experience  is  only  a  part  of  the  whole  sphere 
of  its  domain,  but  the  absolute  totality  of  all  possible  ex 
perience  is  itself  not  experience.  Yet  it  is  a  necessary 
problem  for  Reason,  the  mere  representation  of  which 
requires  concepts  quite  different  from  the  Categories,  whose 
use  is  only  immanent,  or  refers  to  experience,  so  [116]  far 
as  it  can  be  given.  Whereas  the  concepts  of  Reason 
extend  to  the  completeness,  that  is,  the  collective  unity  of 
all  possible  experience,  and  thereby  exceed  every  given 
experience,  and  become  transcendent. 

As  the  understanding  stands  in  need  of  categories  for 
experience,  Reason  contains  in  itself  the  source  of  Ideas, 
by  which  I  mean  necessary  notions,  whose  object  cannot 
be  given  in  any  experience.  The  latter  are  inherent  in  the 
nature  of  Reason,  as  the  former  are  in  that  of  the  under 
standing  ;  and  if  the  categories  carry  with  them  an  illusion 
likely  to  mislead,  in  the  Ideas  it  is  inevitable,  though  it 
certainly  can  be  kept  from  misleading  us. 

As  all  illusion  consists  in  holding  the  subjective  ground 

1  If  we  can  say,  that  a  science  is  acttcal,  at  least  in  the  idea  of  all 
men,  as  soon  as  it  appears  that  the  problems  which  lead  to  it  are 
proposed  to  everybody  by  the  nature  of  human  reason,  and  that  hence 
many  (though  faulty)  essays  in  it  are  always  unavoidable,  then  we  are 
bound  to  say,  that  Metaphysic  is  subjectively  (and  indeed  necessarily) 
actual,  and  therefore  we  justly  ask,  how  is  it  (objectively)  possible. 


116-117]      OF  THE  SYSTEM  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  91 

of  our  judgments  to  be  objective,  a  self-knowledge  of  pure 
reason  in  its  transcendent  (exaggerated)  use  is  the  sole 
preservative  from  the  aberrations  into  which  reason  falls 
when  it  mistakes  its  destination,  and  refers  that  to  the 
object  transcendently,  which  only  regards  its  own  subject 
and  its  guidance  in  all  immanent  use. 

§  41.  The  distinction  of  Ideas,  that  is,  of  pure  concepts 
of  Reason,  from  Categories,  or  pure  concepts  of  the 
understanding,  as  cognitions  of  a  quite  distinct  species, 
origin  and  use,  is  so  important  a  point  in  founding  a 
science  which  is-  to  contain  the  system  of  all  these  a  priori 
cognitions,  that  without  this  distinction  metaphysic  is  ab 
solutely  [117]  impossible,  or  is  at  best  a  random,  bungling 
attempt  to  build  a  castle  in  the  air  without  a  knowledge  of 
the  materials  or  of  their  fitness  for  any  purpose.  Had  the 
Kritik  of  Pure  Reason  done  nothing  but  first  point  out  this 
distinction,  it  had  thereby  contributed  more  to  clear  up  our 
notions  and  to  guide  our  inquiry  in  the  field  of  metaphysic, 
than  all  the  vain  efforts  which  have  hitherto  been  made  to 
satisfy  the  transcendent  problems  of  pure  reason,  without 
ever  surmising  that  we  were  in  quite  another  field  than  that 
of  the  .understanding,  and  hence  classing  concepts  of  the 
understanding  and  those  of  Reason  together,  as  if  they  were 
of  the  same  kind. 

§  42.  All  pure  cognitions  of  the  understanding  have  this 
feature,  that  their  concepts  present  themselves  in  experience, 
and  their  principles  can  be  confirmed  by  it ;  whereas  the 
transcendent  cognitions  of  Reason  cannot,  either  as  Ideas^ 
appear  in  experience,  or  as  propositions  ever  be  confirmed 
or  refuted  by  it.  Hence  whatever  errors  may  slip  in 
unawares,  can  only  be  discovered  by  pure  Reason  itself — 
a  discovery  of  much  difficulty,  because  this  very  Reason 
naturally  becomes  dialectical  by  means  of  its  Ideas,  and 


92  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [117-119 

this  unavoidable  illusion  cannot  beJimjted  bv  any  objective 
and  dogmatical  researches  into  things,  but^py  a  subjective 
investigationof  reason  itself  as  a  source  of  Ideas.  _. 

§  43.  In  the  Kritik  of  Pure  Reason  it  was  always  my 
greatest  care  to  endeavour  not  only  carefully  to  [118]  dis 
tinguish  the  [various]  species  of  cognition,  but  to  derive 
notions  belonging  to  each  one  of  them  from  their  common 
source.  I  did  this  in  order  that  by  knowing  whence  they 
originated,  I  might  determine  their  use  with  safety,  and  also 
have  the  very  novel  but  incalculable  advantage  of  knowing 
the  completeness  of  my  enumeration,  classing,  and  speci 
fication  of  concepts  a  priori,  and  therefore  according  to 
principles.  Without  this  [security]  metaphysic  is  mere 
rhapsody,  in  which  no  one  knows  whether  he  has  enough, 
or  whether  and  where  something  is  still  wanting.  We  can 
indeed  have  this  advantage  only  in  pure  philosophy,  but  of 
this  philosophy  it  constitutes  the  very  essence. 

As  I  had  found  the  origin  of  the  categories  in  the  four 
logical  functions  of  all  the  judgments  of  the  understanding, 
it  was  quite  natural  to  seek  the  origin  of  the  Ideas  in  the 
three  functions  of  the  syllogisms  of  Reason ;  for  as  soon  as 
these  pure  concepts  of  Reason  (the  transcendental  Ideas) 
are  given,  they  could  hardly,  except  they  be  held  innate,  be 
found  anywhere  else,  than  in  the  same  act  of  Reason. 
This,  so  far  as  it  regards  mere  form,  constitutes  the  logical 
element  of  the  syllogisms  of  Reason  ;  but,  so  far  as  it  repre 
sents  the  judgments  of  the  understanding  as  determined 
relatively  to  the  one  or  to  the  other  form  a  priori,  con 
stitutes  transcendental  concepts  of  pure  Reason. 

The  formal  distinction  of  syllogisms  renders  [119]  their 
division  into  categorical,  hypothetical,  and  disjunctive 
necessary.  The  concepts  of  Reason  founded  on  them 
contained  therefore,  first,  the  Idea  of  the  complete  subject 


H9-I20]      OF  THE  SYSTEM  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  93 

(the  substantial) ;  secondly,  the  Idea  of  the  complete  series 
of  conditions ;  thirdly,  the  determination  of  all  concepts  in 
the  Idea  of  a  complete  complex  of  [all]  possible  [being].1 
The  first  Idea  is  psychological,  the  second  cosmological, 
the  third  theological,  and,  as  all  three  give  occasion  to 
Dialectic,  yet  each  in  its  own  way,  the  division  of  the 
whole  Dialectic  of  pure  reason  into  its  Paralogism,  its  Anti 
nomy,  and  its  Ideal,  was  arranged  accordingly.  Through  this 
deduction  we  may  feel  assured  that  all  the  claims  of  pure 
reason  are  completely  represented,  and  that  none  can  be 
wanting ;  because  the  faculty  of  Reason  itself,  whence  they 
all  take  their  origin,  is  thereby  completely  surveyed. 

§  44.  In  these  general  considerations  it  is  also  [120] 
remarkable  that  the  Idea  of  Reason  is  not,  like  the  cate 
gories,  of  any  service  to  the  use  of  our  understanding  in 
experience,  but  with  respect  to  that  use  is  quite  dispensable, 
and  even  an  impediment  to  the  maxims  of  the  rational 
cognition  of  nature,  though  necessary  in  another  aspect  still 
to  be  determined.  Whether  the  soul  is  or  is  not  a  simple 
substance,  is  of  no  consequence  to  us  in  the  explanation  of 
its  phenomena.  For  we  cannot  render  the  notion  of  a 
simple  being  intelligible  by  any  possible  experience  sensu 
ously  or  in  concrete.  The  notion  is  therefore  quite  void  as 
regards  all  hoped-for  insight  into  the  cause  of  phenomena, 

1  In  disjunctive  judgments  we  consider  all  possibility  as  divided  in 
relation  to  a  particular  concept.  The  ontological  principle  of  the 
thorough  determination  of  a  thing  in  general  (viz.,  one  of  all  possible 
opposite  predicates  belongs  to  everything),  which  is  at  the  same  time  the 
principle  of  all  disjunctive  judgments,  presupposes  the  complex  of  all 
possibility,  in  which  the  possibility  of  everything  in  general  is  con 
sidered  as  determined  [reading  bestimmf\.  This  may  serve  as  a  slight 
explanation  of  the  above  proposition  :  that  the  act  of  Reason  in  dis 
junctive  syllogisms  is  formally  the  same  as  that  by  which  it  accomplishes 
the  Idea  of  a  complex  of  all  reality,  which  contains  in  itself  the  positive 
[member]  of  all  [pairs  of]  contradictory  predicates. 


94  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [120-121 

and  cannot  at  all  serve  as  a  principle  of  the  explanation  of 
that  which  internal  or  external  experience  supplies.  So  the 
cosmological  Ideas  of  the  beginning  of  the  world  or  of  its 
eternity  (a  parte  ante)  cannot  be  of  any  greater  service  to  us 
for  the  explanation  of  any  event  in  the  world  itself.  And 
finally  we  must,  according  to  a  right  maxim  of  the  philosophy 
of  nature,  refrain  from  all  explanations  of  the  design  of 
nature,  drawn  from  the  will  of  a  Supreme  Being ;  because 
this  [mode  of  explanation]  is  not  natural  philosophy,  but  an 
acknowledgment  that  we  have  come  to  the  end  of  it.  The  use 
of  these  Ideas,  therefore,  is  quite  distinct  from  that  of  those 
categories  by  which  (and  by  the  principles  built  upon  which) 
experience  itself  first  becomes  possible.  But  our  laborious 
Analytic  of  the  understanding  would  be  [121]  superfluous  if 
we  had  nothing  else  in  view  than  the  mere  cognition  of 
nature  as  it  can  be  given  in  experience ;  for  reason  does  its 
work,  both  in  mathematic  and  in  the  science  of  nature, 
quite  safely  and  well  without  any  of  this  subtile  deduction ; 
our  Kritik  of  the  Understanding  therefore  combines  with 
the  Ideas  of  pure  Reason  for  a  purpose  placed  beyond  the 
empirical  use  of  the  understanding,  which  we  have  already 
declared  to  be  in  this  aspect  totally  impossible,  and  without 
any  object  or  meaning.  But  yet  there  must  be  harmony 
between  that  which  belongs  to  the  nature  of  Reason  and  to 
that  of  the  understanding,  and  the  former  must  contribute 
to  the  perfection  of  the  latter,  and  cannot  possibly  confuse  it. 
The  solution  of  this  question  is  as  follows  :  Pure  reason 
does  not  in  its  Ideas  point  to  particular  objects,  which  lie 
beyond  the  field  of  experience,  but  only  requires  complete 
ness  of  the  use  of  the  understanding  in  the  system  of 
experience.  But  this  completeness  can  be  a  completeness 
of  principles  only,  not  of  intuitions  and  of  objects.  In 
order  however  to  represent  the  Ideas  to  itself  determinately, 


I2I-I23]      OF  THE  SYSTEM  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  95 

Reason  conceives  them  as  the  cognition  of  an  object  which 
[cognition]  is  as  regards  these  rules  completely  determined 
(though  the  object  is  only  an  Idea),  for  the  purpose  of 
bringing  the  cognition  of  the  understanding  as  near  as 
possible  to  the  completeness  which  that  Idea  denotes. 

[122]  Prefatory  Remark  to  the  Dialectic  of  Pure  Reason. 

§  45.  We  have  above  shown  (in  §§33  and  34)  that  the 
purity  of  the  categories  from  all  admixture  of  sensuous 
determinations  may  mislead  reason  into  extending  their  use, 
quite  beyond  all  experience,  to  things  per  se ;  though  as 
these  categories  themselves  find  no  intuition  which  can  give 
them  meaning  or  sense  in  concrete,  they  (as  mere  logical 
functions)  can  represent  a  thing  in  general,  but  not  give  by 
themselves  alone  a  determinate  concept  of  anything.  Such 
hyperbolical  objects  are  distinguished  by  the  appellation  of 
Noiimena,  or  pure  beings  of  the  understanding  (or  better, 
beings  of  thought),  such  as,  for  example,  substance,  but  con 
ceived  without  permanence  in  time,  or  cause,  but  not  acting 
in  time,  etc.  Here  predicates,  that  only  serve  to  make  the 
conformity-to-law  of  experience  possible,  are  applied  to  these 
concepts,  and  yet  they  are  deprived  of  all  the  conditions  of 
intuition,  on  which  alone  experience  is  possible,  and  so  these 
concepts  lose  all  signification. 

There  is  no  danger  of  the  understanding  spontaneously 
making  an  excursion  so  very  wantonly  beyond  its  own 
bounds  into  the  field  of  the  mere  creatures  of  thought,  with 
out  being  impelled  by  foreign  laws.  But  when  Reason, 
which  cannot  be  fully  satisfied  with  any  empirical  use  of  the 
rules  [123]  of  the  understanding,  as  being  always  con 
ditioned,  requires  a  completion  of  this  chain  of  conditions, 
then  the  understanding  is  forced  out  of  its  sphere.  And 


96  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [123-124 

then  it  partly  represents  objects  of  experience  in  a  series  so 
extended  as  no  experience  can  grasp,  partly  even  (with  a 
view  to  complete  the  series)  it  seeks  entirely  beyond  it 
nonmena,  to  which  it  can  attach  that  chain,  and  so,  having 
at  last  escaped  from  the  conditions  of  experience,  make  its 
attitude  as  it  were  final.  These  are  then  the  transcendental 
Ideas,  which,  though  according  to  the  true  but  hidden  ends 
of  the  natural  determination  of  our  reason,  they  may  aim 
not  at  extravagant  concepts,  but  at  unbounded  extension  of 
empirical  use,  yet  seduce  \ablocken\  the  understanding  by 
an  unavoidable  illusion  to  a  transcendent  use,  which,  though 
deceitful,  cannot  be  restrained  within  the  bounds  of  experi 
ence  by  any  resolution,  but  only  by  scientific  instruction 
and  with  much  difficulty. 

I.    The  Psychological  Idea.'1 

§  46.  It  has  been  long  since  observed,  that  in  all  sub 
stances  the  proper  subject,  that  which  remains  after  all  the 
accidents  (as  predicates)  are  abstracted,  consequently  that 
which  is  itself  substantial,  is  unknown,  and  various  com 
plaints  have  been  [124]  made  concerning  these  limits  to 
our  knowledge.  But  we  must  take  care  to  observe,  that 
the  human  understanding  is  not  to  be  blamed  for  its  inability 
to  know  the  substance  of  things,  that  is,  to  determine  it  by 
itself,  but  rather  for  requiring  to  cognise  a  mere  Idea  de- 
terminately,  like  a  given  object.  Pure  reason  requires  us 
to  seek  for  every  predicate  of  a  thing  its  proper  subject,  and 
for  this  subject,  which  is  itself  necessarily  nothing  but  a 
predicate,  its  subject,  and  so  on  indefinitely  (or  as  far  as  we 
can  reach).  But  hence  it  follows,  that  we  must  not  hold 
anything,  at  which  we  can  arrive,  to  be  an  ultimate  subject, 

1   Vide  Kritik,  p.  237  sqq.,  and  Appendix  C  to  this  volume.     M. 


124-125]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  97 

and  that  substance  itself  never  can  be  thought  by  our 
understanding,  however  deep  we  may  penetrate,  even  if  all 
nature  were  unveiled  to  us.  For  the  specific  nature  of  our 
understanding  consists  in  thinking  everything  discursively, 
that  is,  representing  it  by_con£££ts,  and  so  by  ^mere^predi- 
-caiej^to  which  therefore  the  absolute  subject  must  always 
be  wanting.  Hence  all  the  real  properties,  by  which  we 
cognise  bodies,  are  mere  accidents,  not  excepting  impene 
trability,  which  we  can  only  represent  to  ourselves  as  the 
effect  of  a  power  of  which  the  subject  is  unknown  to  us. 

Now  we  appear  to  have  this  substance  in  the  conscious 
ness  of  ourselves  (in  the  thinking  subject),  and  indeed  in  an 
immediate  intuition ;  for  all  the  predicates  of  an  internal 
sense  refer  to  the  ego,  as  [125]  subject,  and  I  cannot  con 
ceive  myself  as  the  predicate  of  any  other  subject.  Hence 
completeness  in  the  reference  of  the  given  concepts  as 
predicates  to  a  subject — not  merely  an  Idea,  but  an  object 
— that  is,  the  absolute  subject  itself,  seems  to  be  given  in 
experience.  But  this  expectation  is  disappointed.  For  the 
Ego  is  not  a  concept,1  but  only  the  indication  of  the  object 
of  the  internal  sense,  so  far  as  we  cognise  it  by  no  further 
predicate.  Consequently  it  cannot  be  in  itself  a  predicate 
of  any  other  thing  ;  but  just  as  little  can  it  be  a  determinate 
concept  of  an  absolute  subject,  but  is,  as  in  all  other  cases, 
only  the  reference  of  the  internal  phenomena  to  their  un 
known  subject.  Yet  this  Idea  (which  serves  very  well,  as  a 
regulative  principle,  totally  to  destroy  all  materialistic  ex 
planations  of  the  internal  phenomena  of  the  soul)  occasions 

1  Were  the  representation  of  the  apperception  (the  Ego)  a  concept,  by 
which  anything  could  be  thought,  it  could  be  used  as  a  predicate  of 
other  things  or  contain  predicates  in  itself.  But  it  is  nothing  more  than 
the  feeling  of  an  existence  without  the  least  definite  notion  [Begriff] 
and  is  only  the  representation  of  that,  to  which  all  thinking  stands  in 
relation  (relatione  accidentis. ) 

II  H 


98  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [125-127 

by  a  very  natural  misunderstanding  a  very  specious  argu 
ment,  which,  from  this  supposed  cognition  of  the  substance 
of  our  thinking  being,  infers  its  nature,  so  far  as  the  know 
ledge  of  it  falls  quite  without  the  complex  of  experience. 

[126]  §4 7.  But  though  this  thinking  self  (the  soul) 
should  be  termed  substance,  as  being  the  ultimate  subject 
of  thinking  which  cannot  be  further  represented  as  the 
predicate  of  another  thing ;  yet  this  concept  remains  quite 
empty  and  without  results,  if  permanence — the  quality 
which  renders  the  concept  of  substances  in  experience  fruit 
ful — cannot  be  deduced  from  it. 

But  permanence  can  never  be  proved  from  the  concept 
of  a  substance,  as  a  thing  per  se,  but  for  the  purposes  of 
experience  only.  This  is  sufficiently  shown  by  the  first 
Analogy  of  Experience,1  and  whoever  will  not  yield  to  this 
proof  may  try  for  himself  whether  he  can  succeed  in  proving, 
from  the  concept  of  a  subject  which  does  not  exist  itself  as 
the  predicate  of  another  thing,  that  its  existence  is  thoroughly 
permanent,  and  that  it  cannot  either  in  itself  or  by  any 
natural  cause  originate  or  be  annihilated.  These  synthetical 
a  priori  propositions  can  never  be  proved  in  themselves,  but 
only  in  reference  to  things  as  objects  of  possible  experience. 

§  48.  If  therefore  from  the  concept  of  the  soul  as  a  sub 
stance,  we  would  infer  its  permanence,  this  can  hold  good 
as  regards  possible  experience  only,  not  [of  the  soul]  as  a 
thing  in  itself  and  beyond  all  possible  experience.  But  life 
is  the  subjective  [127]  condition  of  all  our  possible  ex 
perience,  consequently  we  can  only  infer  the  permanence  of 
the  soul  in  life ;  for  the  death  of  man  is  the  end  of  all  ex 
perience  which  concerns  the  soul  as  an  object  of  experience, 
except  the  contrary  be  proved,  which  is  the  very  question 
in  hand.  The  permanence  of  the  soul  can  therefore  only 
1  Cf.  Kritik,  p.  136  sqq. 


127-128]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  99 

be  proved  where  everybody  grants  it,  during  the  life  of  man. 
But  we  cannot  [establish  it],  as  we  desire  to  do,  after  death ; 
and  for  this  general  reason,  that  the  concept  of  substance, 
so  far  as  it  is  to  be  considered  necessarily  combined  with 
the  concept  of  permanence,  can  be  so  combined  only 
according  to  principles  of  possible  experience,  and  therefore 
for  the  purposes  of  experience  only.1 

[128]  §  49.  That  something  actual  without  us  not  only 
corresponds,  but  must  correspond,  to  our  external  percep 
tions,  can  likewise  be  proved  not  as  a  connexion  of  things 
in  themselves,  but  for  the  purpose  of  experience.  This 
means  : — that  it  certainly  admits  of  proof  that  there  is 
something  empirical,  i.e.  [existing]  as  phenomenon  in  space 
without  us ;  for  we  have  nothing  to  do  with  other  objects 
than  those  which  belong  to  possible  experience ;  because 

1  It  is  indeed  very  remarkable,  how  carelessly  metaphysicians  have 
always  passed  over  the  principle  of  the  permanence  of  substances  with 
out  ever  attempting  a  proof  of  it ;  doubtless  because  they  found  them 
selves  abandoned  by  all  proofs  as  soon  as  they  began  to  deal  with  the 
concept  of  substance.  Common  sense,  which  felt  distinctly  that  with 
out  this  presupposition  no  union  of  perceptions  in  experience  is  possible, 
supplied  the  want  by  a  postulate  ;  for  from  experience  itself  it  never  could 
derive  such  a  principle,  partly  because  substances  cannot  be  so  traced 
in  all  their  alterations  and  dissolutions,  that  the  matter  can  always  be 
found  undiminished,  partly  because  the  principle  contains  necessity, 
which  is  always  the  sign  of  an  a  priori  principle.  People  then  boldly 
applied  this  postulate  to  the  concept  of  soul  as  a  substance,  and  concluded 
a  necessary  continuance  of  the  soul  after  the  death  of  man  (especially  as 
the  simplicity  of  this  substance,  which  is  inferred  from  the  indivisibility 
of  consciousness,  secured  it  from  destruction  by  dissolution).  Had  they 
found  the  genuine  source  of  this  principle — a  discovery  which  requires 
deeper  researches  than  they  were  ever  inclined  to  make — they  would 
have  seen,  that  the  law  of  the  permanence  of  substances  has  place  for 
the  purposes  of  experience  only,  and  hence  can  hold  good  of  things,  so 
far  as  they  are  to  be  cognised  and  conjoined  with  others  in  experience, 
but  never  independently  of  all  possible  experience,  and  consequently 
cannot  hold  good  of  the  soul  after  death. 


ioo  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [128-129 

objects,  which  cannot  be  given  us  in  any  experience,  are 
nothing  to  us.  That  which  is  intuited  in  space,  is  empiric 
ally  without  [outside]  me,  and  space,  together  with  all  the 
I  phenomena  which  it  contains,  belongs  to  the  representations, 
1  whose  connexion  according  to  laws  of  experience  proves 
1  their  objective  truth,  just  as  the  connexion  of  the  phenomena 
of  the  internal  sense  proves  the  actuality  of  my  soul  (as  an 
object  of  the  internal  sense).  I  am  therefore  conscious  by 
means  of  external  experience  of  the  actuality  of  bodies,  as 
external  [129]  phenomena  in  space,  in  the  same  manner  as 
I  am,  by  means  of  the  internal  experience,  of  the  existence 
of  my  soul  in  time.1  For  this  (soul)  I  only  cognise  as  an 
object  of  the  internal  sense  by  phenomena  that  constitute 
an  internal  state,  and  of  which  the  being  per  se,  which  forms 
the  basis  of  these  phenomena,  is  unknown  to  me.  Cartesian 
idealism  therefore  does  nothing  but  distinguish  external  ex 
perience  from  dreaming ;  and  the  conformity  to  law  (as  a 
criterion  of  its  truth)  of  the  former,  from  the  irregularity  and 
the  false  illusion  of  the  latter.  In  both  it  presupposes  space 
and  time  as  conditions  of  the  existence  of  objects,  and  it 
only  inquires  whether  the  objects  of  the  external  senses, 
which  we  when  awake  put  in  space,  are  as  actually  to  be 
found  in  it,  as  the  object  of  the  internal  sense,  the  soul,  is 
in  time;  that  is,  whether  experience  carries  with  it  sure 
criteria  to  distinguish  it  from  imagination.  Now  this  doubt 
may  easily  be  removed,  and  we  always  do  remove  it  in 
common  life  by  investigating  the  connexion  of  phenomena 
in  both  [space  and  time]  according  to  universal  laws  of  ex- 

1  It  is  to  be  observed  that  Kant  here  places  his  refutation  of  Cartesian 
idealism  in  the  place  which  it  held  in  the  First  Edition  of  the  Kritik. 
In  the  Second  Edition  it  was  transferred  to  an  earlier,  and  I  think  a 
better,  place,  in  connexion  with  the  Postulates  of  Empirical  Thought. 
M. 


129-131]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  101 

perience,  and  we  cannot  doubt,  when  [130]  the  representa 
tion  of  external  things  thoroughly  agrees  therewith,  that 
they  constitute  truthful  experience.  Material  idealism,  in 
which  phenomena  are  considered  as  such  only  according  to 
their  connexion  in  experience,  may  accordingly  be  very 
easily  refuted  ;  and  it  is  just  as  sure  an  experience,  that  bodies 
exist  without  us  (in  space),  as  that  I  myself  exist  according 
to  the  representation  of  the  internal  sense  (in  time) :  for  the 
notion  ivithout  [outside]  us,  only  signifies  existence  in  space. 
However  as  the  Ego  in  the  proposition, '  I  am,  means  not 
only  the  object  of  internal  intuition  (in  time),  but  the  sub 
ject  of  consciousness,  just  as  body  means  not  only  external 
intuition  (in  space),  but  the  thing  in  itself ,  which  is  the  basis 
of  this  phenomenon ;  [as  this  is  the  case]  the  question, 
whether  bodies  (as  phenomena  of  the  external  sense)  exist 
as  bodies  apart  from  my  thoughts^  may  without  any  hesita 
tion  be  denied  in  nature.  But  the  question,  whether  I  my 
self  as  a  phenomenon  of  the  internal  sense  (the  soul  according 
to  empirical  psychology)  exist  apart  from  my  faculty  of  re 
presentation  in  time,  is  an  exactly  similar  inquiry,  and  must 
likewise  be  answered  in  the  negative.  And  in  this  manner 
everything,  when  it  is  reduced  to  its  true  meaning,  is  decided 
and  certain.  The  formal  (which  I  have  also  called  tran 
scendental)  actually  abolishes  the  material,  or  Cartesian, 
Idealism.  For  if  space  be  nothing  but  a  form  of  my 
sensibility,  it  is  as  a  [131]  representation  in  me  just  as 
actual  as  I  myself  am,  and  nothing  but  the  empirical  truth 
of  the  representations  in  it  remains  for  consideration.  But, 
if  this  is  not  the  case,  if  space  and  the  phenomena  in  it 
are  something  existing  out  of  us,  then  all  the  criteria  of 
experience  beyond  our  perception  can  never  prove  the 
actuality  of  these  objects  without  us.1 

1  The  foregoing  paragraph  is  an  excellent  commentary  on  the  Refuta- 


102  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [131-132 

II.    The  Cosmological  Ideal 

§  50.  This  product  of  pure  Reason  in  its  transcendent 
use  is  its  most  remarkable  phenomenon,  and  the  most 
powerful  of  all  means  of  rousing  philosophy  from  its  dog 
matic  slumber,  and  of  exciting  it  to  undertake  the  arduous 
task  of  the  Kritik  of  the  Reason  itself. 

I  term  this  Idea  cosmological,  because  it  only  takes  its 
objects  from  the  sensible  world,  and  does  not  use  any 
other  than  those  whose  object  is  given  to  sense,  con 
sequently  is  so  far  at  home  [immanent],  not  transcendent, 
and  therefore  so  far  not  an  Idea;  whereas,  to  conceive  the 
soul  as  a  simple  substance,  already  'means  to  conceive 
such  an  object  (the  Simple)  [132]  as  cannot  be  presented  to 
the  senses.  Yet  the  cosmological  Idea  extends  the  con 
nexion  of  the  conditioned  with  its  condition  (whether  the 
connexion  is  mathematical  or  dynamical)  so  far,  that  ex 
perience  never  can  keep  up  with  it.  It  is  therefore  with 
regard  to  this  point  always  an  Idea,  whose  object  never 
can  be  adequately  given  in  any  experience. 

§  5 1.  In  the  first  place,  the  use  of  a  system  of  categories 
becomes  here  so  obvious  and  unmistakable,  that  even  if 
there  were  not  several  other  proofs  of  it,  this  alone  would 
sufficiently  prove  it  indispensable  in  the  system  of  pure 
reason.  There  are  only  four  such  transcendent  Ideas,  as 
there  are  so  many  classes  of  categories ;  in  each  of  which, 
however,  they  refer  only  to  the  absolute  completeness  of 
the  series  of  the  conditions  for  a  given  conditioned.  And 
conformably  to  these  cosmological  Ideas  there  are  only 

tion  of  (Cartesian,  not  Berkleian)  idealism  in  the  Second  Edition  of  the 
Kritik,  and  corroborates  my  assertion  that  it  has  been  absurdly  miscon 
ceived.     It  is  not  creditable  to  German  Kantians  that  they  have  pro 
pagated  this  blunder.     M. 
1  Cf.  Kritik,  p.  256. 


132-133]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  103 

four  kinds  of  dialectical  assertions  of  pure  Reason,  which, 
as  they  are  dialectical,  thereby  prove,  that  to  each  of  them, 
on  equally  specious  principles  of  pure  reason,  a  contra 
dictory  assertion  stands  opposed.  As  all  the  metaphysical 
art  of  the  most  subtile  distinction  cannot  prevent  this 
opposition,  it  compels  the  philosopher  to  recur  to  the  first 
sources  of  pure  reason  itself.  This  Antinomy,  not  arbitrarily 
invented,  but  founded  in  the  nature  of  human  reason,  and 
hence  unavoidable  and  never  ceasing,  contains  the  following 
four  theses  together  with  their  antitheses  : 

[i33]  i. 

Thesis. 

The  World  has,  as  to  Time  and  Space,  a  Beginning  (Bounds). 

Antithesis. 
The  World  is,  as  to  Time  and  Space,  infinite. 

2. 

Thesis. 
Every  thing  in  the  World  consists  of  simple  [parts]. 

Antithesis. 
There  is  nothing  simple,  but  every  thing  is  composite. 

3- 

Thesis. 

There  are  in  the  World  Causes  [acting]  through  Freedom 
[Liberty]. 

Antithesis. 
There  is  no  Liberty,  but  all  is  Nature. 


io j  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [133- 134 

4- 

Thesis. 

In  the  Series  of  the  World-Causes  there  is  some  necessary 
Being. 

Antithesis. 

There  is  Nothing  necessary  in  the  World,  but  in  this  Series 
All  is  contingent. 

[134]  §  52.  a.  Here  we  have  the  most  singular  pheno 
menon  of  human  reason,  no  other  instance  of  which  can 
be  shown  in  any  other  use  [of  reason].-  If  we,  as  is 
commonly  done,  represent  to  ourselves  the  phenomena  of 
the  sensible  world  as  things  in  themselves, — if  we  assume 
the  principles  of  their  combination  as  principles  universally 
valid  of  things  in  themselves  and  not  merely  of  experience 
(as  is  usually,  nay  without  our  Kritik,  unavoidably  done), 
—there  arises  an  unexpected  conflict,  which  never  can  be 
removed  in  the  common  dogmatical  way ;  because  the 
thesis,  as  well  as  the  antithesis,  can  be  shown  by  equally 
clear,  evident,  and  irresistible  proofs — for  I  pledge  myself 
as  to  the  correctness  of  all  these  proofs — and  reason 
therefore  perceives  that  it  is  divided  with  itself,  a  state  at 
which  the  sceptic  rejoices,  but  which  must  cause  the  critical 
philosopher  reflection  and  uneasiness. 

§  52.  b.  We  may  make  divers  blunders  in  Metaphysic 
without  any  fear  of  being  detected  in  falsehood.  For  we 
never  can  be  refuted  by  experience  if  we  but  avoid  self- 
contradiction,  which  in  synthetical,  though  purely  invented 
propositions,  may  be  done  whenever  the  concepts,  which 
we  connect,  are  mere  Ideas,  that  cannot  be  given  (as  to 
their  whole  content)  in  experience.  For  how  can  we  make 
out  by  experience,  whether  the  world  is  from  eternity  or 


134-136]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  TORE  REASON  105 

had  a  beginning,  whether  matter  is  infinitely  divisible  or 
consists  of  simple  parts?  Such  [135]  concepts  cannot  be 
given  in  any  experience,  however  great,  and  consequently 
the  falsehood  either  of  the  positive  or  the  negative  proposi 
tion  cannot  be  discovered  by  this  test. 

The  only  possible  case,  in  which  Reason  reveals  unin 
tentionally  its  secret  Dialectic,  which  it  falsely  announces 
as  Dogmatic,  is  when  it  grounds  an  assertion  upon  a 
universally  admitted  principle,  and  from  another  equally 
admitted  infers,  with  the  greatest  accuracy  of  inference,  the 
exact  contrary.  This  is  actually  here  the  case  with  regard 
to  four  natural  Ideas  of  Reason,  whence  four  assertions  on 
the  one  side,  and  as  many  counter -assertions  on  the  other 
arise,  each  strictly  following  from  universally-acknowledged 
principles.  Thus  the  dialectical  illusion  of  pure  Reason 
appears  in  the  use  of  these  principles,  [an  illusion]  which 
must  otherwise  be  for  ever  concealed. 

This  is  therefore  a  decisive  experiment,  which  must 
necessarily  expose  any  error  lying  hidden  in  the  assump 
tions  of  Reason.1  Contradictory  propo-  [136]  sitions  cannot 
both  be  false,  except  the  concept,  which  is  the  subject  of 
both,  is  self- contradictory ;  for  example,  the  propositions, 
*  a  square  circle  is  round,  and  a  square  circle  is  not  round,' 
are  both  false.  For,  as  to  the  former  it  is  false,  that  the 
circle  is  round,  because  it  is  quadrangular ;  and  it  is 

1  I  therefore  request  the  critical  reader  to  make  this  Antinomy  his 
chief  study,  because  nature  itself  seems  to  have  established  it  with  a 
view  to  stagger  reason  in  its  daring  pretentions,  and  to  force  it  to  self- 
examination.  For  every  proof,  which  I  have  given,  as  well  of  the 
thesis  as  of  the  antithesis,  I  undertake  to  be  responsible,  and  thereby  to 
show  the  certainty  of  the  inevitable  Antinomy  of  reason.  As  soon  as 
the  reader  is  brought  by  this  curious  phenomenon  to  recur  to  the  proof 
of  the  presumption  upon  which  it  rests,  he  will  feel  himself  constrained 
to  investigate  the  first  foundation  of  all  the  cognition  of  pure  reason  with 
me  more  thoroughly. 


io6  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [136-137 

likewise  false,  that  it  is  not  round,  that  is,  angular,  because 
it  is  a  circle.  For  the  logical  mark  of  the  impossibility  of 
a  concept  consists  in  this,  that  if  we  presuppose  it,  two 
contradictory  propositions  both  become  false  ;  consequently, 
as  no  middle  between  them  is  conceivable,  nothing  at  all  is 
thought  by  that  concept. 

§  52.  c.  The  first  two  Antinomies,  which  I  call  mathe 
matical,  because  they  are  concerned  with  the  addition  or 
division  of  the  homogeneous,  are  founded  on  such  a  self- 
contradictory  concept ;  and  hence  I  explain  how  it  happens, 
that  the  Thesis  in  both,  as  well  as  the  Antithesis  [addition 
and  subdivision]  is  false. 

When  I  speak  of  objects  in  time  and  in  space,  it  is  not 
of  things  in  themselves,  of  which  I  know  nothing,  but  of 
things  as  phenomena,  that  is,  of  experience,  as  the  particular 
way  of  cognising  objects  which  is  vouchsafed  to  man. 
\  Accordingly  [137]  I  must  not  say  of  what  I  think  in  time 
or  in  space,  that  in  itself,  and  beyond  [outside]  these  my 
thoughts,  it  exists  in  space  and  in  time ;  for  in  that  case  I 
should  contradict  myself;  l^ca_u£e_space^m^Jiipe,_tp^ether 
with  -lfoe"^henomena-Uii_^theiTiJL_are  nothing  existing  in 
themselves  and  without  [outside]  my  representations.,  but 
are  themselves  only  modes  of  representation,  and  it  is 
palpably  contradictory  to  say,  that  a  mere  mode  of  repre 
sentation  exists  without  our  representation.  Objects  of  the 
senses  therefore  exist  only  in  experience  ;  whereas  to  give 
them  a  self- subsisting  existence  apart  from  experience  or 
before  it,  is  merely  to  represent  to  ourselves,  that  experience 
actually  exists  apart  from  experience  or  before  it. 

Now  if  I  inquire  after  the  quantity  of  the  world,  as  to 
space  and  time,  it  is  equally  impossible,  as  regards  all  my 
notions,  to  declare  it  infinite,  or  to  declare  it  finite.  For 
neither  assertion  can  be  contained  in  experience,  because 


137-139]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  107 

experience  either  of  an  infinite  space,  or  of  an  infinite  time 
elapsed,  or  again,  of  the  bounding  of  the  world  by  a  void 
space  or  an  antecedent  void  time,  is  impossible ;  these  are 
only  Ideas.  This  quantity  of  the  world,  which  is  determined 
in  either  way,  should  therefore  exist  in  the  world  per  se  apart 
from  all  experience.  But  this  contradicts  the  notion  of  a 
world  of  sense,  which  is  merely  a  complex  of  the  phenomena 
whose  existence  and  connexion  occur  only  in  our  repre-  [138] 
sentations,  that  is,  in  experience,  since  this  latter  is  not  a  thing 
per  se,  but  is  itself  a  mere  mode  of  representation.  Hence 
it  follows,  that  as  the  concept  of  an  absolutely  existing  world 
of  sense  is  self-contradictory,  the  solution  of  the  problem 
concerning  its  quantity,  whether  attempted  affirmatively  or 
negatively,  is  always  false. 

The  same  holds  good  of  the  second  Antinomy,  which 
relates  to  the  division  of  phenomena.  For  these  are  mere 
representations,  and  the  parts  exist  merely  in  their  representa 
tion,  consequently  in  the  division,  or  in  a  possible  experience 
where  they  are  given,  and  the  division  reaches  only  as  far 
as  this  latter  reaches.  To  assume  that  a  phenomenon,  e.g. 
that  of  body,  contains  in  itself  before  all  experience  all  the 
parts,  which  any  possible  experience  can  ever  reach,  is  to 
give  a  mere  phenomenon,  which  can  exist  only  in  experience, 
withal  an  existence  previous  to  experience ;  or  to  say,  that 
mere  representations  exist  before  they  occur  in  our  faculty  of 
representation,  which  assertion  is  self-contradictory,  as  also 
every  solution  of  our  misunderstood  problem,  whether  we 
maintain,  that  bodies  in  themselves  consist  of  an  infinite 
number  of  parts,  or  of  a  finite  number  of  simple  parts. 

§  5  3.  In  the  first  (the  mathematical)  class  of  Antinomies 
the  falsehood  of  the  assumption  consists  in  representing 
that  what  is  self-contradictory  (a  phenomenon  as  a  thing 
per  se)  can  be  united  in  one  [139]  concept.  But,  as  to  the 


io8  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [139-140 

second  (the  dynamical)  class  of  Antinomies,  the  falsehood 
of  the  representation  consists  in  representing  as  contradictory 
what  can  be  united;  so  that,  as  in  the  former  case,  the 
opposed  assertions  are  both  false,  in  this  case,  on  the  other 
hand,  where  they  are  opposed  to  one  another  by  mere 
misunderstanding,  they  may  both  be  true. 

For  mathematical  connexion  necessarily  presupposes 
homogeneity  of  what  is  connected  (in  the  concept  of 
quantity),  but  this  is  by  no  means  requisite  in  the 
dynamical.  When  the  quantum  of  wriat  is  extended  is  in 
question,  all  the  parts  must  be  homogeneous  with  one 
another  and  with  the  whole ;  whereas,  in  the  connexion  of 
cause  and  effect,  homogeneity  may  indeed  likewise  be 
found,  but  is  not  necessary ;  for  the  concept  of  causality 
(by  means  of  which  something  is  posited  through  something 
else  quite  distinct  from  it),  at  all  events,  does  not  require  it. 

If  the  objects  of  the  sensuous  world  are  taken  for  things 
in  themselves,  and  the  above  laws  of  nature  for  the  laws  of 
things  in  themselves,  the  contradiction  would  be  unavoid 
able.  So  also,  if  the  subject  of  freedom  is,  like  other 
objects,  represented  as  mere  phenomenon,  the  contradiction 
is  just  as  unavoidable,  for  the  same  predicate  is  at  once 
affirmed  and  denied  of  the  same  kind  of  object  in  the  same 
sense.  But  if  natural  necessity  is  referred  [140]  merely  to 
phenomena,  and  freedom  merely  to  things  in  themselves, 
no  contradiction  arises,  if  we  at  once  assume,  or  admit  both 
kinds  of  causality,  however  difficult  or  impossible  it  may  be 
to  make  the  latter  kind  conceivable. 

In  the  phenomenon  every  effect  is  an  event,  or  some 
thing  that  happens  in  time;  it  must,  according  to  the 
universal  law  of  nature,  be  preceded  by  a  determination  of 
the  causality  (or  state)  of  its  cause,  which  follows  according 
to  a  constant  law.  But  this  determination  of  the  cause  to 


140-141]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  109 

[produce]  causality  must  likewise  be  something  that  happens, 
or  takes  place ;  the  cause  must  have  begun  to  act,  otherwise 
no  succession  between  it  and  the  effect  could  be  conceived. 
Otherwise  the  effect,  as  well  as  the  causality  of  the  cause, 
would  have  always  existed.  Therefore  the  determination 
of  the  cause  to  act  must  also  have  originated  among 
phenomena,  and  must  consequently,  as  well  as  its  effect,  be 
an  event,  which  must  again  have  its  cause,  and  so  on  ;  hence 
natural  necessity  must  be  the  condition,  on  which  effective 
causes  are  determined.  Whereas  if  freedom  is  to  be  a 
property  of  certain  causes  of  phenomena,  it  must,  as  regards 
these,  which  are  events,  be  a  faculty  of  beginning  them 
from  itself  (sponte],  that  is,  without  the  causality  of  the 
cause  itself  beginning,  and  hence  without  requiring  any 
other  ground  to  determine  its  beginning.  But  then  the 
cause,  as  to  its  causality,  must  not  rank  under  time-determina- 
[141]  tions  of  its  state,  that  is,  not  be  a  phenomenon,  and 
must  be  considered  a  thing  per  se,  and  its  effects  only  as 
phenomena.1  If  we  can  think  such  an  influence  of  the 

1  The  Idea  of  freedom  occurs  only  in  the  relation  of  the  intellectual, 
as  cause,  to  the  phenomenon,  as  effect.  Hence  we  cannot  attribute 
freedom  to  matter  in  regard  to  the  incessant  action  by  which  it  fills  its 
space,  though  this  action  takes  place  from  an  internal  principle.  We 
can  likewise  find  no  notion  of  freedom  suitable  to  pure  rational  beings, 
for  instance,  to  God,  so  far  as  His  action  is  immanent.  For  His  action, 
though  independent  of  external  determining  causes,  is  determined  in 
His  eternal  reason,  that  is,  in  the  divine  nature.  It  is  only,  if  something 
is  to  begin  by  an  action,  and  so  the  effect  occurs  in  the  sequence  of  time, 
or  in  the  world  of  sense  (e.g.  the  beginning  of  the  world),  that  we  can 
put  the  question,  whether  the  causality  of  the  cause  must  likewise  itself 
begin,  or  whether  the  cause  can  originate  an  effect  without  its  causality 
itself  beginning.  In  the  former  case  the  concept  of  this  causality  is  a 
concept  of  natural  necessity,  in  the  latter,  that  of  freedom.  From  this 
the  reader  will  see,  that,  as  I  explained  freedom  to  be  the  faculty  of 
beginning  an  event  spontaneously,  I  have  exactly  hit  the  notion  which 
is  the  problem  of  Metaphysic. 


i  io  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [141-142 

things  of  understanding  \Verstandeswesen\  on  phenomena 
without  contradiction,  then  natural  necessity  will  attach  to 
all  connexion  of  cause  and  effect  in  the  sensuous  world,  but, 

(on  the  other  hand,  freedom  can  be  granted  to  such  cause, 
as  is  itself  not  a  phenomenon  (though  the  basis  of  one). 
Nature  therefore  and  freedom  can  without  contradiction  be 
attributed  to  the  very  same  thing,  [142]  but  in  different 
relations — on  one  side  as  a  phenomenon,  on  the  other  as 
a  thing  per  se. 

We  have  in  us  a  faculty,  which  not  only  stands  in  con 
nexion  with  its  subjective  determining  grounds,  that  are  the 
natural  causes  of  its  actions,  and  is  so  far  the  faculty  of  a 
being  that  itself  belongs  to  phenomena  :  but  is  [also  a 
faculty]  referred  to  objective  grounds,  that  are  only  ideas, 
*so  far  as  they  can  determine  this  faculty,  a  connexion  which 
is  expressed  by  the  word  ought.  This  faculty  is  called 
Reason,  and,  so  far  as  we  consider  a  being  (man)  entirely 
according  to  this  objectively  determinable  reason,  he  cannot 
be  considered  as  a  being  of  sense,  but  this  property  is  that 
of  a  thing  per  se,  of  which  we  cannot  comprehend  the 
possibility — I  mean  how  the  ought  (which  however  has 
never  yet  taken  place)  should  determine  its  activity,  and  can 
become  the  cause  of  actions,  whose  effect  is  a  phenomenon 
in  the  sensible  world.  Yet  the  causality  of  Reason  would 
be  freedom  with  regard  to  the  effects  in  the  sensuous  world, 
so  far  as  we  can  consider  objective  grounds,  which  are  them 
selves  Ideas,  as  determining  in  regard  to  it.  For  its  action 
in  that  case  would  not  depend  upon  subjective  conditions, 
consequently  not  upon  those  of  time,  and  of  course  not 
upon  the  law  of  nature,  which  serves  to  determine  them, 
because  grounds  of  reason  give  to  actions  the  rule  universally, 
according  to  principles,  without  the  influence  of  the  circum 
stances  of  either  time  or  place. 


143-144]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  in 

[143]  What  I  adduce  here  is  merely  meant  as  an  example 
to  make  the  thing  intelligible,  and  does  not  necessarily  belong 
to  our  problem,  which  must  be  decided  from  mere  concepts, 
independently  of  the  properties  which  we  meet  in  the  actual 
world. 

Now  I  may  say  without  contradiction  :  that  all  the  actions 
of  rational  beings,  so  far  as  they  are  phenomena  (occurring 
in  any  experience),  are  subject  to  the  necessity  of  nature ; 
but  the  same  actions,  as  regards  merely  the  rational  subject 
and  its  faculty  of  acting  according  to  mere  Reason,  are  free. 
For  what  is  required  for  the  necessity  of  nature  ?  Nothing 
farther  than  the  determinability  of  every  event  in  the  world 
of  sense  according  to  constant  laws,  that  is,  a  reference  to 
cause  in  the  phenomenon  ;  in  this  process  the  thing  in  itself 
at  its  basis  and  its  causality  remain  unknown.  But  I  say, 
that  the  law  of  nature  remains,  whether  the  rational  being  is 
the  cause  oLlhe  ejects^jn^the_se^uous  world  from  reason, 
that  is,  throughjreedom,  or  whether  it  does  not  determine 
them  on  grounds  of  reason.  For,  if  the  former  is  the  case, 
the  action  is  performed  according  to  Maxims,  the  effect  of 
which  as  phenomenon  is  always  conformable  to  constant 
laws  ;  if  the  latter  is  the  case,  and  the  action  not  performed 
on  principles  of  Reason,  it  is  subjected  to  the  empirical 
laws  of  the  sensibility,  and  in  both  cases  the  effects  are  con 
nected  according  to  constant  laws ;  more  than  this  we  do 
not  require  or  know  concerning  [144]  natural  necessity.  But 
in  the  former  case  reason  is  the  cause  of  these  laws  of  nature, 
and  therefore  free  ;  in  the  latter  the  effects  follow  according 
to  mere  natural  laws  of  sensibility,  because  reason  does  not 
influence  it ;  but  reason  itself  is  not  determined  on  that 
account  by  the  sensibility,  and  is  therefore  free  in  this  case 
too.  Freedom  is  therefore  no  hindrance  to  natural  law  in 
phenomena,  neither  does  this  law  interfere  with  the  freedom 


ii2  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [144-145 

of  the  practical  use  of  Reason,  which  is  connected  with 
things  in  themselves,  as  determining  grounds. 

And  thus  we  rescue  practical  freedom,  or  that  in  which 
Reason  has  causality  according  to  objectively  determining 
grounds,  and  do  not  curtail  natural  necessity  in  the  least 
with  regard  to  the  very  same  effects,  as  phenomena.  The 
same  remarks  may  be  serviceable  for  the  illustration  of  what 
we  had  to  say  concerning  transcendental  freedom  and  its 
union  with  natural  necessity  (in  the  same  subject,  but  not 
taken  in  the  same  reference).  For,  as  to  this,  every  be 
ginning  of  the  action  of  a  being  from  objective  causes 
regarded  as  determining  grounds,  is  always  a  first  beginning, 
though  the  same  action  is  in  the  series  of  phenomena  only 
a  subaltern  beginning,  which  must  be  preceded  by  a  state  of 
the  cause,  which  determines  it,  and  is  itself  determined  in 
the  same  manner  by  another  immediately  preceding.  Thus 
i  we  are  able,  in  rational  beings,  or  in  beings  generally,  so  far 
as  their  causality  is  determined  in  them  [145]  as  things  per 
se,  to  imagine  a  faculty  of  beginning  from  itself  a  series  of 
states,  without  falling  into  contradiction  with  the  laws  of 
nature.  For  the,relation  of  the  action  to  objectiye_grQunds 
of  reason  is  not  a  time-relation  ;  in  this  case  that  which 
determines  the  causality  does  not  precede  in  time  the  action, 
because  such  determining  grounds  represent  not  a  reference 
to  objects  of  sense,  e.g.  to  causes  in  the  phenomenon,  but 
[they  represent]  determining  causes,  as  things  per  se,  which 
do  not  rank  under  conditions  of  time.  And  in  this  way  the 
action,  with  regard  to  the  causality  of  reason,  can  be  con 
sidered  as  a  first  beginning  in  respect  to  the  series  of 
phenomena,  and  yet  also  as  a  merely  subordinate  beginning. 
We  may  therefore  consider  it  (without  contradiction)  in  the 
former  aspect  as  free,  but  in  the  latter  (as  it  is  merely 
phenomenon)  as  subject  to  natural  necessity. 


145-146]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  113 

As  to  \hsfourth  Antinomy,  it  is  solved  in  the  same  way 
as  the  conflict  of  reason  with  itself  in  the  third.  For,  pro 
vided  the  cause  in  the  phenomenon  is  distinguished  from  the! 
cause  of  the  phenomena  (so  far  as  it  can  be  thought  as  a  thing* 
-ber  se\  both  propositions  are  perfectly  reconcilable  :  the  one, 
that  there  is  nowhere  in  the  sensuous  world  a  cause 
(according  to  similar  laws  of  causality),  whose  existence  is 
absolutely  necessary ;  the  other,  that  this  world  is  neverthe 
less  connected  with  a  Necessary  Being  as  its  cause  (but  of 
another  kind  and  according  to  [146]  another  law).  The 
incompatibility  of  these  propositions  entirely  rests  upon  the 
mistake  of  extending  what  is  valid  merely  of  phenomena^ to 
things  inthemselves,  and  in  general  confusing  both  in  one 
concept. 

§  54.  This  is  the  arrangement  and  this  the  solution  of 
the  whole  Antinomy,  in  which  reason  finds  itself  involved 
in  the  application  of  its  principles  to  the  sensible  world,  the 
former  of  which  alone  (the  mere  arrangement)  would  be  of 
considerable  use  in  promoting  the  knowledge  of  human 
reason,  even  though  the  solution  failed  to  fully  satisfy  the 
reader,  who  has  here  to  combat  a  natural  illusion,  which  has 
been  but  recently  exposed  to  him,  and  which  he  had  hitherto 
always  regarded  as  true.  For  one  result  at  least  is  unavoid 
able.  As  it  is  quite  impossible  to  prevent  this  conflict  of 
reason  with  itself — so  long  as  the  objects  of  the  sensible 
world  are  taken  for  things  in  themselves,  and  not  for  mere 
phenomena,  which  they  are  in  fact — the  reader  is  thereby 
compelled  to  examine  over  again  the  deduction  of  all  our  a 
priori  cognition  and  the  proof  which  I  have  given  of  my 
deduction  in  order  to  come  to  a  decision  on  the  question. 
This  is  all  I  require  at  present ;  for  when  in  this  occupation 
he  shall  have  thought  himself  far  enough  into  the  nature 
of  pure  reason,  the  only  notions  by  which  the  solution  of 
ii  i 


ii4  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [146-148 

the  conflict  of  reason  is  possible,  will  become  sufficiently 
familiar  to  him.  Without  this  preparation  I  cannot  [147] 
expect  a  hasty  assent  even  from  the  most  attentive  reader. 

III.   The  Theological  Idea.1 

§  55.  The  third  transcendental  Idea,  which  affords 
matter  for  the  most  important,  but,  if  pursued  only  specula- 
tively,  transcendent  and  thereby  dialectical  use  of  Reason, 
is  the  Ideal  of  pure  Reason.  Reason  in  this  case  does  not, 
as  with  the  psychological  and  the  cosmological  Ideas,  begin 
from  experience,  and  err  by  exaggerating  its  grounds^  in 
striving  to  attain,  if  possible,  the  absolute  completeness  of 
their  series.  It  rather  breaks  totally  with  experience,  and 
from  mere  concepts  of  what  constitutes  the  absolute  com 
pleteness  of  a  thing  in  general,  consequently  by  means  of 
the  Idea  of  a  most  perfect  primal  Being,  it  proceeds  to 
determine  the  possibility  and  therefore  the  actuality  of  all 
other  things.  And  so  the  mere  presupposition  of  a  Being, 
who  is  conceived  not  in  the  series  of  experience,  yet  for  the 
purposes  of  experience — for  the  sake  of  comprehending  its 
connexion,  order,  and  unity — that  is,  the  Idea,  is  more  easily 
distinguished  from  the  concept  of  the  understanding  here, 
than  in  the  former  cases.  Hence  we  can  easily  expose  the 
dialectical  illusion  which  arises  from  our  making  the  subject 
ive  conditions  of  our  thinking  objective  conditions  [148]  of 
things  themselves,  and  [so  holding]  a  necessary  hypothesis 
for  the  satisfaction  of  our  reason  to  be  a  dogma.  As  the 
observations  of  the  Kritik  on  the  pretensions  of  transcend 
ental  theology  are  intelligible,  clear,  and  decisive,  I  have 
nothing  more  to  add  on  the  subject. 

1  Cf.  Kritik,  p.  350  sqq. 


148-149]        THE  DIALECTIC  OF  PURE  REASON  115 


General  Remark  on  the  Transcendental  Ideas. 

§  56.  The  objects,  which  are  given  us  by  experience,  are 
in  many  respects  incomprehensible,  and  many  questions,  to 
which  the  law  of  nature  leads  us,  when  carried  beyond  a 
certain  point  (though  quite  conformably  to  the  laws  of 
nature),  admit  of  no  answer ;  as  for  example  the  question  : 
why  substances  attract  one  another?  But  if  we  entirely 
quit  nature,  or  in  pursuing  its  combinations,  exceed  all 
possible  experience,  and  so  involve  ourselves  in  mere  Ideas, 
we  cannot  then  say  that  the  object  is  incomprehensible,  and 
that  the  nature  of  things  proposes  to  us  insoluble  problems. 
For  we  are  not  then  concerned  with  nature  or  in  general 
with  given  objects,  but  with  concepts,  which  have  their 
origin  merely  in  our  reason,  and  with  mere  creatures  of 
thought.  As  regards  these  all  the  problems  that  arise  from 
our  notions  of  them  must  be  solved,  because  of  course  reason 
can  and  must  give  a  full  account  of  its  own  procedure.1  As 
the  psycho-  [149]  logical,  cosmological,  and  theological  Ideas 
are  nothing  but  pure  concepts  of  Reason,  which  cannot  be 
given  in  any  experience,  the  questions  which  reason  asks  us 
about  them  are  put  to  us  not  by  the  objects,  but  by  mere 
maxims  of  our  reason  for  the  sake  of  its  own  satisfaction. 

1  And  therefore  Platner  in  his  Aphorisms  acutely  says  (§§  728,  729), 
'If  reason  be  a  criterion,  no  concept,  which  is  incomprehensible  to  human 
reason,  can  be  possible.  Incomprehensibility  has  place  in  what  is  actual 
only.  Here  incomprehensibility  arises  from  the  insufficiency  of  the 
acquired  Ideas. '  It  therefore  only  sounds  paradoxical,  but  is  otherwise 
not  strange  to  say,  that  in  nature  there  is  much  incomprehensible  (e.g. 
the  faculty  of  generation)  but  if  we  mount  still  higher,  and  even  go 
beyond  nature,  everything  again  becomes  comprehensible  ;  for  we  then 
quit  entirely  the  objects,  which  can  be  given  us,  and  occupy  ourselves 
merely  about  Ideas,  in  which  occupation  we  can  easily  comprehend  the 
law  that  reason  prescribes  by  them  to  the  understanding  for  its  use  in 
experience,  because  the  law  is  the  reason's  own  production. 


ii6  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [149-150 

They  must  collectively  be  capable  of  complete  answers, 
which  is  done  by  showing  that  they  are  principles  which 
bring  our  use  of  the  understanding  into  thorough  agreement, 
completeness,  and  synthetical  unity,  and  that  they  so  far 
hold  good  of  experience  only,  but  of  experience  as  &jMkole_- 
But  though  an  absolute  whole  of  experience  is  impossible, 
yet  the  Idea  of  a  whole  of  cognition  according  to  principles 
must  above  all  things  afford  our  knowledge  a  particular  sort 
of  unity,  that  of  a  system,  without  which  it  is  nothing  but 
patchwork,  and  cannot  be  used  for  the  highest  end  (which 
can  only  be  the  systemf-atising]  of  all  ends) — I  [150]  do 
not  here  mean  only  the  practical,  but  also  the  highest  end 
of  the  speculative  use  of  reason. 

The  transcendental  Ideas  therefore  express  the  peculiar 
destination  of  reason  as  a  principle  of  systematic  unity  in 
the  use  of  the  understanding.  Yet  [we  are  apt  to  consider] 
this  unity  of  the  mode  of  cognition  as  attached  to  the  object 
of  cognition,  if  we  regard  that  which  is  merely  regulative 
to  be  constitutive,  and  if  we  persuade  ourselves,  that  we  can 
by  means  of  these  Ideas  enlarge  our  cognition  transcend- 
ently,  or  far  beyond  all  possible  experience.  But  [if  we 
do]  so — as  this  unity  only  serves  to  render  experience  within 
itself  as  nearly  complete  as  possible,  that  is,  to  limit  its  pro 
gress  by  nothing  that  cannot  belong  to  experience — it  is 
a  mere  misunderstanding  in  our  estimate  of  the  proper 
destination  of  our  reason  and  of  its  principles,  a  Dialectic, 
which  both  confuses  the  empirical  use  of  reason,  and  also 
sets  reason  at  variance  with  itself. 

CONCLUSION 

On  the  determination  of  the  Bounds  of  Pure  Reason 
§  57.  After  all  the  very  cogent  proofs  already  adduced,  it 


150-152]  THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  117 

were  absurd  for  us  to  hope  to  know  more  of  any  object, 
than  belongs  to  the  possible  experience  of  it,  or  to  lay  claim 
to  the  least  atom  of  knowledge  about  anything  not  assumed 
to  be  an  object  of  possible  experience,  which  would  deter- 
[151]  mine  it  according  to  the  constitution  it  has  in  itself. 
For  how  could  we  compass  this  determination,  as  time, 
space,  and  the  Categories,  and  still  more  all  the  concepts 
formed  by  empirical  intuition  or  perception  in  the  sensible 
world,  have  and  can  have  no  other  use,  than  to  make  experi 
ence  possible.  And  if  this  condition  is  not  imposed  on  the 
pure  concepts  of  the  understanding,  they  do  not  determine 
any  object,  and  have  no  meaning  whatever. 

But  it  would  be  on  the  other  hand  a  still  greater 
absurdity  if  we  conceded  no  things  per  se,  or  set  up  our 
experience  for  the  only  possible  mode  of  knowing  things, 
our  intuition  in  space  and  in  time  for  the  only  possible 
intuition,  and  our  discursive  understanding  for  the  archetype 
"of  every  possible  understanding  ;  in  fact  if  we  wished  to  have 
the  principles  of  the  possibility  of  experience  considered 
universal  conditions  of  things  in  themselves. 

Our  principles,  which  limit  the  use  of  reason  merely  to 
possible  experience,  might  in  this  way  become  transcendent f, 
and  the  limits  of  our  reason  be  set  up  as  limits  of  the 
possibility  of  things  themselves  •  (as  Hume's  dialogues  may 
illustrate),  if  a  careful  Kritik  did  not  guard  the  bounds  of 
our  reason  with  respect  to  its  empirical  use,  and  set  a  limit 
to  its  pretensions.  Scepticism  originally  arose  from  meta- 
physic  and  its  licentious  dialectic.  At  first  it  might,  merely 
to  favour  the  empirical  use  of  [152]  reason,  announce  every 
thing  that  transcends  this  use  as  worthless  and  deceitful ;  but 
by  and  by,  when  it  was  perceived  that  the  very  same 
principles  that  are  used  in  experience,  insensibly,  and 
apparently  with  the  same  right,  led  still  further  than  experi- 


n8  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [152-153 

ence  extends,  then  men  began  to  doubt  even  the  propositions 
of  experience.  But  here  there  is  no  danger ;  for  sound  sense 
will  doubtless  always  assert  its  rights.  A  certain  confusion, 
however,  arose  in  science  which  cannot  determine  how  far 
reason  is  to  be  trusted,  and  why  only  so  far  and  no  further, 
and  this  confusion  can  only  be  cleared  up  and  all  future  re 
lapses  obviated  by  a  formal  determination,  on  principle,  of 
the  boundary  of  the  use  of  our  reason. 

We  cannot  indeed,  beyond  all  possible  experience,  form 
a  determinate  notion  of  what  things  in  themselves  may  be. 
Yet  we  are  not  at  liberty  to  abstain  entirely  from  inquiring 
into  them  ;  for  experience  never  satisfies  reason  fully,  but  in 
answering  questions,  refers  us  further  and  further  back,  and 
leaves  us  dissatisfied  with  regard  to  their  complete  solution. 
This  any  one  may  gather  from  the  Dialectic  of  pure  reason, 
which  therefore  has  its  good  subjective  grounds.  If  we  can 
advance,  as  regards  the  nature  of  our  soul,  as  far  as  a  clear 
consciousness  of  the  subject,  and  the  conviction,  that  its 
phenomena  cannot  be  materialistically  explained,  who  can 
refrain  from  asking  what  the  soul  [153]  really  \eigentlicJi\ 
is,  and,  if  no  concept  of  experience  suffices  for  the  purpose, 
from  accounting  for  it  by  a  concept  of  Reason  (that  of  a 
simple  immaterial  being),  though  we  cannot  by  any  means 
prove  its  objective  reality?  Who  can  satisfy  himself  with 
mere  empirical  knowledge  in  all  the  cosmological  questions 
of  the  duration  and  of  the  quantity  of  the  world,  of  freedom 
or  of  natural  necessity,  as  every  answer  given  on  principles 
of  experience  begets  a  fresh  question,  which  likewise  requires 
its  answer,  and  thereby  clearly  shows  the  insufficiency  of  all 
physical  modes  of  explanation  to  satisfy  reason  ?  Finally, 
who  is  there  that  does  not  see,  in  the  thorough  contingency 
and  dependence  of  all  his  thoughts  and  assumptions  on  mere 
principles  of  experience,  the  impossibility  of  stopping  there  ? 


153-154!  THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  119 

And  who  does  not  feel  himself  compelled,  notwithstanding 
all  interdictions  against  losing  himself  in  transcendent  Ideas, 
to  seek  tranquillity  and  contentment  beyond  all  the  concepts 
which  he  can  vindicate  by  experience,  in  the  concept  of  a 
single  Being  ?  The  possibility  indeed  of  this  Idea  in  itself, 
we  cannot  conceive,  but  at  the  same  time  we  cannot  refute 
it,  because  it  relates  to  a  mere  being  of  the  understanding, 
and  without  it  reason  must  needs  remain  for  ever  dis 
satisfied. 

Bounds  (in  extended  beings)  always  presuppose  a  space 
existing  outside  a  certain  determinate  place,  and  inclosing  it ; 
limits  do  not  require  this,  [154]  but  are  mere  negations,  which 
affect  a  quantity,  so  far  as  it  is  not  absolutely  complete. 
But  our  reason,  as  it  were,  sees  a  space  around  it  for  the 
cognition  of  things  in  themselves,  though  it  (reason)  never 
can  have  determinate  notions  of  them,  and  is  limited  to 
phenomena  only. 

As  long  as  the  cognition  of  reason  is  homogeneous, 
determinate  bounds  to  it  are  inconceivable.  In  mathematic 
and  in  natural  philosophy  human  reason  admits  of  limits, 
but  not  of  bounds,  viz.  that  something  indeed  lies  without 
it,  at  which  it  can  never  arrive,  but  not  that  it  will  at 
any  point  find  completion  in  its  internal  progress.  The 
enlarging  of  our  views  in  mathematic,  and  the  possibility 
of  new  discoveries,  are  infinite ;  and  the  same  is  the  case 
with  the  discovery  of  new  properties  of  nature,  of  new  powers 
and  laws,  by  continued  experience  and  its  rational  combina 
tion.  But  limits  cannot  be  mistaken  here,  for  mathematic 
refers  to  phenomena  only,  and  what  cannot  be  an  object  of 
sensuous  intuition,  such  as  the  concepts  of  metaphysic  and 
of  morals,  lies  entirely  without  its  sphere,  and  it  can  never 
lead  to  them  ;  neither  does  it  require  them.  It  is  therefore 
not  a  continual  progress  and  an  approximation  towards  these 


120  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [154-156 

sciences,  and  there  is  not,  as  it  were,  any  point  or  line  of 
contact.  Natural  philosophy  will  never  discover  to  us  the 
internal  constitution  of  things,  which  is  not  phenomenon, 
yet  can  serve  as  the  ultimate  ground  of  [155]  explanation  of 
phenomena ;  but  that  science  does  not  require  this  for  its 
physical  explanations.  Nay  even  if  such  grounds  should  be 
offered  from  other  sources  (for  instance,  the  influence  of 
immaterial  beings),  they  must  be  rejected  and  not  used 
in  the  progress  of  its  explanations.  For  these  explana 
tions  must  only  be  grounded  upon  that  which  as  an 
object  of  sense  can  belong  to  experience,  and  be  brought 
into  connexion  with  our  actual  perceptions  and  empirical 
laws. 

But  Metaphysic  leads  us  towards  bounds  in  the  dialectical 
attempts  of  pure  reason  (not  undertaken  arbitrarily  or 
wantonly,  but  excited  by  the  nature  of  reason  itself).  And 
the  transcendental  Ideas,  as  they  do  not  admit  of  evasion, 
and  are  never  capable  of  realisation,  serve  to  point  out  to  us 
actually  not  only  the  bounds  of  the  pure  use  of  reason,  but 
also  the  way  to  determine  them.  Such  is  the  end  and  the 
use  of  this  natural  predisposition  of  our  reason,  which  has 
brought  forth  Metaphysic  as  its  pet,  whose  generation,  like 
every  other  in  the  world,  is  not  to  be  ascribed  to  blind 
chance,  but  to  an  original  germ,  wisely  organised  for  great 
ends.  For  Metaphysic,  in  its  fundamental  features,  perhaps 
more  than  any  other  science,  is  placed  in  us  by  nature  itself, 
and  cannot  be  considered  the  production  of  a  voluntary 
choice  or  a  casual  enlargement  in  the  progress  of  experience 
from  which  it  is  quite  distinct. 

[156]  Reason  finds  of  itself  no  satisfaction  by  all  its  con 
cepts  and  laws  of  the  understanding,  which  suffice  for 
empirical  use,  or  withm  the  sensible  world,  as  ever-recurring 
questions  deprive  us  of  all  hope  of  their  complete  solution. 


156-157!  THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  121 

The  transcendental  Ideas,  which  have  that  completion  in 
view,  are  "such  problems  of  Reason.  But  it  sees  clearly, 
that  the  sensuous  world  cannot  contain  this  completion, 
neither  consequently  can  all  the  concepts,  which  serve 
merely  for  understanding  the  world  of  sense,  such  as  space 
and  time,  and  whatever  we  have  adduced  under  the  name 
of  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding.  The  sensuous  world 
is  nothing  but  a  chain  of  phenomena  connected  according 
to  universal  laws  ;  it  has  therefore  no  subsistence  by  itself;  it 
is  not  the  thing  in  itself,  and  consequently  must  point  to 
that  which  contains  the  basis  of  this  experience,  to  beings 
which  cannot  be  cognised  merely  as  phenomena,  but  as 
things  per  se.  In  the  cognition  of  them  alone  reason  can 
hope  to  satisfy  its  desire  of  completeness  in  proceeding  from 
the  conditioned  to  its  conditions. 

We  have  indicated  (§§  33,  34)  the  limits  of  reason  with 
regard  to  all  cognition  of  mere  creatures  of  thought.  Now 
only — since  the  transcendental  Ideas  compel  us  to  approach 
them,  and  so  have  led  us,  as  it  were,  only  to  the  contact  of 
the  full  space  (of  experience)  with  the  void  (of  which  we 
can  know  nothing,  noumend) — now  only  we  can  [157]  deter 
mine  the  bounds  of  pure  reason.  For  in  all  bounds  there 
is  something  positive  (e.g.,  a  surface  is  the  boundary  of 
corporeal  space,  and  is  therefore  itself  a  space,  a  line  is  a 
space,  which  is  the  boundary  of  the  surface,  a  point  the 
boundary  of  the  line,  but  yet  always  a  place  in  space), 
whereas  limits  contain  mere  negations.  The  limits  pointed 
out  in  those  paragraphs  are  not  enough  after  we  have  dis 
covered  that  beyond  them  there  still  lies  something  (though 
we  can  never  cognise  what  it  is  in  itself).  For  the  question 
now  is,  What  is  the  attitude  of  our  reason  in  this  connexion 
of  what  we  know  with  what  we  do  not,  and  never  shall,  know  ? 
This  is  an  actual  connexion  of  a  known  thing  with  one  quite 


122  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPIIYSIC          [157-158 

unknown  (and  which  will  always  remain  so),  and  though 
what  is  unknown  should  not  become  the  least  more  known 
— which  we  cannot  even  hope — yet  the  notion  of  this  con 
nexion  must  be  definite,  and  capable  of  being  rendered 
distinct. 

We  must  therefore  conceive  an  immaterial  being,  an 
intelligible  world  \Verstandeswelf^  and  a  Supreme  Being 
(mere  noumena\  because  in  them  only,  as  things  in  them 
selves,  Reason  finds  that  completion  and  satisfaction,  which 
it  never  can  hope  for  in  the  derivation  of  phenomena  from 
their  homogeneous  grounds,  and  because  these  actually 
refer  to  something  distinct  from  them  (and  totally  hetero 
geneous),  as  phenomena  always  presuppose  a  thing  [158] 
per  se,  and  therefore  indicate  it,  whether  we  can  know 
more  of  it  or  not. 

But  as  we  can  never  cognise  these  beings  of  under 
standing  as  they  are/^  se,  that  is,  determinately,  yet  must 
assume  them  as  regards  the  sensible  world,  and  connect 
them  with  it  by  reason,  we  are  at  least  able  to  think  this 
connection  by  means  of  such  concepts  as  express  their 
relation  to  the  world  of  sense.  Yet  if  we  represent  to 
ourselves  a  being  of  the  understanding  by  nothing  but  pure 
concepts  of  the  understanding,  we  then  indeed  represent 
nothing  determinate  to  ourselves,  consequently  our  concept 
has  no  signification ;  but  if  we  think  it  by  properties 
borrowed  from  the  sensuous  world,  it  is  no  longer  a  being 
of  understanding,  but  is  conceived  as  a  phenomenon,  and 
belongs  to  the  sensible  world.  Let  us  take  an  instance 
from  the  notion  of  the  Supreme  Being. 

Our  notion  of  the  Deity  \deistischer  Begriff}  is  quite 
a  pure  concept  of  Reason,  but  represents  only  a  thing 
containing  all  realities,  without  being  able  to  determine 
any  one  of  them  ;  because  for  that  purpose  an  example 


158-160]  THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  123 

must  be  taken  from  the  sensuous  world,  in  which  case  we 
should  have  an  object  of  sense  only,  not  something  quite 
heterogeneous,  which  cannot  be  such.  For  suppose  I 
attribute  to  the  Supreme  Being  understanding,  [159]  for 
instance ;  I  have  no  concept  of  an  understanding  other 
than  my  own,  one  that  must  receive  intuitions  by  the 
senses,  and  which  is  occupied  in  bringing  them  under  rules 
of  the  unity  of  consciousness.  Then  the  elements  of  my 
concept  would  always  lie  in  the  phenomenon ;  I  should 
however  by  the  insufficiency  of  the  phenomena  be  neces 
sitated  to  go  beyond  them  to  the  concept  of  a  being  which 
neither  depends  upon  phenomena,  nor  is  bound  up  with 
them  as  conditions  of  its  determination.  But  if  I  separate 
understanding  from  sensibility  to  obtain  a  pure  under 
standing,  then  nothing  remains  but  the  mere  form  of 
thinking  without  intuition,  by  which  form  alone  I  can 
cognise  nothing  determinate,  and  consequently  no  object. 
For  that  purpose  I  must  conceive  another  understanding, 
which  should  intuite  objects,  but  of  which  I  have  not  the 
least  notion ;  because  the  human  understanding  is  dis 
cursive,  and  can  only  cognise  by  means  of  general  concepts. 
And  the  very  same  difficulties  arise  if  we  attribute  a  will  to 
the  Supreme  Being ;  for  we  have  this  concept  only  by 
drawing  it  from  our  internal  experience,  and  therefore  from 
our  dependence  for  satisfaction  upon  objects  whose  existence 
we  require  ;  and  so  the  notion  rests  upon  sensibility,  which 
is  totally  repugnant  to  the  pure  concept  of  the  Supreme 
Being. 

Hume's  objections  to  deism  are  weak,  and  affect 
[160]  only  the  proofs,  and  not  the  deistical  assertion  itself. 
But  as  regards  theism,  which  depends  on  a  stricter 
determination  of  the  Deist's  merely  transcendent  concept 
of  the  Supreme  Being,  they  are  very  strong,  and  after  [or 


i24  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [160-161 

according  as]  this  concept  is  formed,  in  certain  (in  fact  in 
all  common)  cases  irrefragable.  Hume  always  insists,  that 
by  the  mere  concept  of  an  original  being,  to  which  we 
apply  only  ontological  predicates  (eternity,  omnipresence, 
omnipotence),  we  think  nothing  determinate,  and  that 
properties  which  can  yield  a  concept  in  concrete  must  be 
superadded ;  that  it  is  not  enough  to  say,  it  is  Cause,  but 
we  must  explain  the  nature  of  its  causality,  for  example, 
that  of  an  understanding  .and  of  a  will.  He  then  begins 
his  attacks  on  the  assertion  itself,  theism,  as  he  had  pre 
viously  directed  his  battery  only  against  the  proofs  of  deism, 
an  attack  which  is  not  very  dangerous  in  its  consequences. 
All  his  dangerous  arguments  refer  to  anthropomorphism, 
which  he  holds  to  be  inseparable  from  theism,  and  to 
make  it  absurd  in  itself;  but  if  the  former  be  abandoned, 
the  latter  must  vanish  with  it,  and  nothing  remain  but 
deism,  of  which  nothing  can  come,  which  is  of  no  value, 
and  which  cannot  serve  as  any  foundation  to  religion  or 
morals.  If  this  anthropomorphism  were  really  unavoidable, 
no  proofs  whatever  of  the  existence  of  a  Supreme  Being, 
even  were  they  all  granted,  could  determine  for  us  the 
[161]  concept  of  this  Being  without  involving  us  in  con 
tradictions. 

If  we  connect  with  the  command  to  avoid  all  tran 
scendent  judgments  of  pure  reason,  the  command  (which 
apparently  conflicts  with  it)  to  proceed  to  concepts  that  lie 
beyond  the  field  of  its  immanent  (empirical)  use,  we 
discover  that  both  can  subsist  together,  but  exactly  at  the 
boundary  of  all  lawful  use  of  reason.  For  this  boundary 
belongs  as  well  to  the  field  of  experience,  as  to  that  of  the 
beings  of  thought,  and  we  are  thereby  taught,  as  well,  how 
these  so  remarkable  Ideas  serve  merely  for  marking  the 
bounds  of  human  reason.  [Thus  we  are  told]  on  the  one 


161-163]          THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  125 

hand  not  to  extend  cognition  of  experience  without  bounds, 
as  if  nothing  but  mere  world  remained  for  us  to  cognise, 
and  yet,  on  the  other  hand,  not  to  transgress  the  bounds  of 
experience,  and  to  think  of  judging  about  things  beyond 
them,  as  things  in  themselves. 

But  we  stop  at  this  boundary  if  we  limit  our  judgment 
merely  to  the  relation  which  the  world  may  have  to  a 
Being  whose  very  concept  lies  beyond  all  the  knowledge 
which  we  can  attain  within  the  world.  For  we  then  do 
not  attribute  to  the  Supreme  Being  any  of  the  properties 
in  themselves ;  by  which  we  represent  objects  of  experience, 
and  thereby  avoid  dogmatic  anthropomorphism;  but  we 
attribute  them  to  His  relation  to  the  world,  and  allow 
ourselves  a  symbolical  anthropomorphism,  [162]  which  in 
fact  concerns  language  only,  and  not  the  object  itself. 

If  I  say  that  we  are  compelled  to  consider  the  world, 
as  if  it  were  the  work  of  a  Supreme  Understanding  and 
Will,  I  really  say  nothing  more,  than  that  a  watch,  a  ship, 
a  regiment,  bears  the  same  relation  to  the  watchmaker,  the 
shipbuilder,  the  commanding  officer,  as  the  world  of  sense 
(or  whatever  constitutes  the  substratum  of  this  complex  of 
phenomena)  does  to  the  Unknown,  which  I  do  not  hereby 
cognise  as  it  is  in  itself,  but  as  it  is  for  me  or  in  relation  to 
the  world,  of  which  I  am  a  part. 

§  58.  Such  a  cognition  is  analogical,  which  does  not 
signify,  as  is  commonly  understood,  an  imperfect  similarity 
of  two  things,  but  a  perfect  similarity  of  relations  between 
two  quite  dissimilar  things.1  [163]  By  means  of  this 

1  There  is  an  analogy  between  the  juridical  relation  of  human  actions* 
and  the  mechanical  relation  of  motive  powers  ;  I  never  can  do  anything 
to  another  man  without  giving  him  a  right  to  do  the  same  to  me  on  the 
same  conditions ;  as  no  body  can  act  with  its  motive  power  on  another 
body  without  thereby  occasioning  the  other  to  react  equally  against  it. 


126  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [163-164 

analogy,  however,  there  remains  a  concept  of  the  Supreme 
Being  sufficiently  determined  for  us,  though  we  have  left 
out  everything  that  could  determine  it  absolutely  or  in  itself ; 
for  we  determine  it  as  regards  the  world  and  as  regards 
ourselves,  and  more  we  do  not  require.  The  attacks  which 
Hume  makes  upon  those  who  would  determine  this  concept 
absolutely,  by  taking  the  materials  for  so  doing  from  them 
selves  and  the  world,  do  not  affect  us  ;  and  he  cannot  object 
to  us,  that  we  have  nothing  left  if  we  give  up  the  objective 
anthropomorphism  of  the  concept  of  the  Supreme  Being. 

For  let  us  assume  at  the  outset  (as  Hume  in  his  dia 
logues  makes  Philo  grant  Cleanthes),  as  a  necessary 
hypothesis,  the  deistical  concept  of  the  First  Being,  in  which 
this  Being  is  thought  by  the  mere  ontological  predicates  of 
substance,  of  cause,  etc.  This  must  be  done,  because  reason, 
actuated  in  the  sensible  world  by  mere  conditions,  which 
are  themselves  always  conditional,  cannot  otherwise  have 
any  satisfaction,  and  it  therefore  can  be  done  without  falling 
into  anthropomorphism  (which  transfers  predicates  from  the 
world  of  sense  to  a  Being  quite  distinct  from  the  world),  as 
those  predicates  [which  we  propose  [164]  to  use]  are  mere 
categories,  which,  though  they  do  not  give  a  determinate 
concept  of  Him,  yet  give  a  concept  not  limited  to  any 
conditions  of  sensibility.  [Granting  this  then]  nothing 

Here  right  and  motive  power  are  quite  dissimilar  things,  but  in  their 
relation  there  is  complete  similarity.  By  means  of  such  an  analogy 
I  can  obtain  a  notion  of  the  relation  of  things  which  absolutely  are 
unknown  to  me.  For  instance,  as  the  promotion  of  the  fortune  of 
children  (  =  a)  is  to  the  love  of  parents  (  =  b),  so  the  welfare  of  the 
human  species  (  =  c)  is  to  that  unknown  [quality]  in  God  (  =  x),  which 
we  call  love ;  not  as  if  it  had  the  least  similarity  to  any  human 
inclination,  but  because  we  can  suppose  its  relation  to  the  world  to  be 
similar  to  that  which  things  of  the  world  bear  one  another.  But  the 
concept  of  relation  in  this  case  is  a  mere  category,  viz.  the  concept  of 
cause,  which  has  nothing  to  do  with  sensibility. 


164-165]          THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  127 

can  prevent  our  predicating  of  this  Being  a  causality 
through  Reason  with  regard  to  the  world,  and  thus 
passing  to  theism,  without  being  forced  to  attribute  to 
Him  in  Himself  this  Reason,  as  a  property  inhering  in  Him. 
For  as  to  the  former,  the  only  possible  way  of  prosecuting 
the  use  of  reason  in  the  world  of  sense  (as  regards  all 
possible  experience,  in  complete  harmony  with  itself,) 
to  the  highest  point,  is  to  assume  a  Supreme  Reason 
as  a  cause  of  all  the  connexions  in  the  world  :  such  a 
principle  must  be  thoroughly  advantageous  to  our  Reason, 
but  can  hurt  it  nowhere  in  its  natural  use.  Secondly, 
Reason  is  thereby  not  transferred  as  a  property  to  the  First 
Being  in  Himself,  but  to  His  relation  to  the  world  of  sense, 
and  so  anthropomorphism  is  entirely  avoided.  For  nothing 
is  considered  here  but  the  Cause  of  the  rational  form 
[  Vernunftfonn\  which  is  perceived  everywhere  in  the  world, 
and  reason  is  attributed  to  the  Supreme  Being,  so  far  as  it 
contains  the  ground  of  this  rational  form  of  the  world,  but 
analogically  only,  that  is,  so  far  as  this  expression  shows 
merely  the  relation,  which  the  Supreme  Cause  unknown  to 
us  has  to  the  world,  in  order  to  determine  everything  in  it 
conformably  to  reason  in  the  highest  degree.  We  are 
thereby  kept  from  using  this  [human]  attri-[i65]  bute, 
Reason,  for  the  purpose  of  conceiving  God  by  means  of  it, 
instead  of  conceiving  the  world  in  the  manner  which  is  ne 
cessary,  in  order  to  have  the  greatest  possible  systematic  use 
of  reason  with  regard  to  it}-  We  thereby  acknowledge,  that 
the  Supreme  Being  is  quite  inscrutable  and  even  incogit- 
able  in  any  determinate  way  as  to  what  He  is  per  se.  We 
are  thereby  kept,  on  the  one  hand,  from  making  a  tran 
scendent  use  of  the  concepts  which  we  have  of  reason  as  an 

1  This  whole  section  is  very  inaccurately  and  confusedly  written. 
The  italics  in  this  sentence  are  mine.     M. 


128  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [165-166 

efficient  cause  (by  means  of  the  will),  in  order  to  determine  the 
Divine  Nature  by  properties,  which  are  only  borrowed  from 
human  nature,  and  from  losing  ourselves  in  gross  and 
extravagant  notions ;  and  on  the  other  hand  [we  are  kept] 
from  deluging  the  contemplation  of  the  world  with  hyper- 
physical  modes  of  explanation  according  to  our  notions  of 
human  reason,  which  we  transfer  to  God,  and  so  losing  for 
this  contemplation  its  proper  destination,  according  to  which 
it  should  be  a  rational  study  of  mere  nature,  and  not  a  pre 
sumptuous  derivation  of  its  phenomena  from  a  Supreme 
Reason.  The  expression  suited  to  our  feeble  notions  is, 
that  we  conceive  the  world  as  if  it  came,  as  to  its  existence 
and  internal  determination,  from  a  Supreme  Reason,  by 
which  notion  we  both  cognise  the  constitution,  which  belongs 
to  it  (the  world)  [166]  itself,  yet  without  pretending  to  de 
termine  the  nature  of  its  cause  per  se,  and  on  the  other 
hand  we  place  the  ground  of  this  constitution  (of  the 
rational  form  in  the  world)  in  the  relation  of  the  Supreme 
Cause  to  the  world,  without  finding  the  world  sufficient  by 
itself  for  that  purpose.1 

And  thus  the  difficulties,  which  seem  to  oppose  theism, 
disappear  by  combining  with  Hume's  principle — '  not  to 
carry  the  use  of  reason  dogmatically  beyond  the  field  of  all 
possible  experience ' — this  other  principle,  which  he  quite 
overlooked  :  '  not  to  consider  the  field  of  experience  as  one 
which  bounds  itself  in  the  eye  of  our  reason.'  The  Kritik 

1  I  may  say,  that  the  causality  of  the  Supreme  Cause  holds  the  same 
place  with  regard  to  the  world  that  human  reason  does  with  regard  to 
its  works  of  art.  Here  the  nature  of  the  Supreme  Cause  itself  remains 
unknown  to  me  :  I  only  compare  its  effects  (the  order  of  the  world) 
which  I  know,  and  their  conformity  to  reason,  to  the  effects  of  human 
reason  which  I  also  know  ;  and  hence  I  term  the  former  reason,  with 
out  attributing  to  it  on  that  account  what  I  understand  in  man  by  this 
term,  or  attaching  to  it  anything  else  known  to  me,  as  its  property. 


I66-I68]  THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  129 

of  pure  Reason  here  points  out  the  true  mean  between 
dogmatism,  which  Hume  combats,  and  scepticism,  which 
he  would  substitute  for  it — a  mean  which  is  not  like  other 
means  that  we  find  advisable  to  determine  for  ourselves  as 
it  were  mechanically  (by  adopting  something  from  one  side 
and  something  from  the  other),  and  by  which  nobody  is 
taught  a  [167]  better  way,  but  such  a  one  as  can  be  ac 
curately  determined  on  principles. 

§  59.  At  the  beginning  of  this  observation  I  made  use 
of  the  metaphor  of  a  boundary,  in  order  to  establish  the 
limits  of  reason  in  regard  to  its  suitable  use.  The  world  of 
sense  contains  merely  phenomena,  which  are  not  things  in 
themselves,  which  (noumena)  therefore  the  understanding 
must  assume.  In  our  Reason  both  are  comprised,  and  the 
question  is,  How  does  reason  proceed  to  bound  the  under 
standing  as  regards  both  these  fields  ?  Experience,  which 
contains  all  that  belongs  to  the  sensuous  world,  does  not 
bound  itself ;  it  only  attains  from  every  conditioned  to  some 
other  equally  conditioned  object.  Its  boundary  must  lie 
quite  without  it,  and  this  field  is  that  of  the  pure  beings  of 
the  understanding.  But  this  field,  so  far  as  the  determina 
tion  of  the  nature  of  these  beings  is  concerned,  is  an  empty 
space  for  us,  and  if  dogmatically-determined  concepts  alone 
are  in  question,  we  cannot  pass  out  of  the  field  of  possible 
experience.  But  as  a  boundary  itself  is  something  positive, 
which  belongs  as  well  to  that  which  lies  within,  as  to  the 
space  that  lies  without  the  given  complex,  it  is  still  an 
actual  positive  cognition,  which  reason  only  acquires  by 
enlarging  itself  to  this  boundary,  yet  without  attempting  to 
pass  it ;  because  it  there  finds  itself  in  presence  of  an  empty 
space,  in  which  it  can  conceive  forms  of  things,  but  not 
things  themselves.  [168]  But  the  bounding  of  the  field  of 
the  understanding  by  something,  which  is  otherwise  un- 

II  K 


130  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [168-169 

known  to  it,  is  still  a  cognition  which  remains  to  reason 
even  at  this  standpoint,  and  by  which  it  is  neither  shut  up 
within  the  sensible,  nor  does  it  stray  without  it,  but  confines 
itself,  as  befits  the  knowledge  of  a  boundary,  to  the  relation 
between  that  which  lies  without  it,  and  that  which  is  con 
tained  within  it. 

Natural  theology  is  a  concept  of  that  sort  at  the 
boundary  of  human  reason,  because  we  are  obliged  to  look 
beyond  this  boundary  to  the  Idea  of  Supreme  Being  (and, 
in  morals  to  that  of  an  intelligible  world  also).  [We  do 
this]  not  in  order  to  determine  anything  relatively  to  this 
mere  being  of  the  understanding,  and  consequently  beyond 
the  world  of  sense,  but  in  order  to  guide  the  use  of  reason 
within  it  according  to  principles  of  the  greatest  possible 
(theoretical  as  well  as  practical)  unity.  For  this  purpose 
we  make  use  of  the  reference  of  the  world  of  sense  to  a 
self- sufficient  reason,  as  the  cause  of  all  its  connexions. 
But  [we  do  this]  not  in  order  merely  to  invent  a  being  for 
ourselves,  but,  as  beyond  the  sensible  world  there  must  be 
something  thought  only  by  the  pure  understanding,  to 
determine  that  something  in  this  particular  way,  though  only 
of  course  according  to  analogy. 

And  thus  there  remains  our  original  proposition,  which 
is  the  result  of  the  whole  Kritik :  'that  reason  [169]  by  all 
its  a  priori  principles  never  teaches  us  anything  more  than 
objects  of  possible  experience,  and  even  of  these  nothing 
more  than  can  be  cognised  in  experience.'  But  this 
limitation  does  not  prevent  the  reason  leading  us  to  the 
objective  boundary  of  experience,  viz.  to  the  reference  to 
something  which  is  not  itself  an  object  of  experience,  but  is 
the  ground  of  all  experience.  Reason  does  not  however 
teach  us  anything  concerning  the  thing  in  itself:  it  only 
instructs  us  as  regards  its  own  complete  and  noblest  use  in 


169-170]  THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  131 

the  field  of  possible  experience.  But  this  is  all  that  can  be 
reasonably  desired  in  the  present  case,  and  with  which  we 
have  cause  to  be  satisfied. 

§  60.  Thus  we  have  fully  exhibited  Metaphysic  as  it  is 
actually  given  in  the  natural  predisposition  of  human  reason, 
and  in  that  which  constitutes  the  essential  end  of  its 
pursuit,  [and  have  explained  it]  according  to  its  subjective 
possibility.  Yet  we  have  found,  that  this  merely  natural 
use  of  such  a  predisposition  of  our  reason,  if  no  discipline 
arising  only  from  a  scientific  Kritik  bridles  and  sets  limits 
to  it,  involves  us  in  transcendent,  either  apparently  or  really 
conflicting,  dialectical  syllogisms.  We  here  also  found  this 
fallacious  Metaphysic  not  only  unnecessary  as  regards  the 
promotion  of  our  knowledge  of  nature,  but  even  disadvan 
tageous  to  it.  There  still  therefore  remains  a  problem 
worthy  of  solution,  to  find  out  the  natural  ends  intended 
by  [170]  this  disposition  to  transcendent  concepts  in  our 
reason,  because  everything  that  lies  in  nature  must  be 
originally  intended  for  some  useful  purpose. 

Such  an  inquiry  is  here  out  of  place ;  and  I  acknow 
ledge,  that  what  I  can  say  about  it  is  conjecture  only, 
like  every  speculation  about  the  first  ends  of  nature.  It 
may  be  allowed  me  in  this  case  only,  as  the  question  does 
not  concern  the  objective  validity  of  metaphysical  judg 
ments,  but  our  natural  predisposition  to  them,  and  therefore 
belongs  to  anthropology,  outside  the  system  of  Metaphysic. 

When  I  [consider1]  all  the  transcendental  Ideas,  the 
complex  of  which  constitutes  the  peculiar  problem  of 
natural  pure  reason,  and  compels  it  to  quit  the  mere 
contemplation  of  nature,  to  transcend  all  possible  experience, 
and  in  this  endeavour  to  produce  the  thing  (be  it  knowledge 
or  nonsense)  called  Metaphysic,  I  think  I  perceive  that  the 
1  There  is  no  verb  in  the  original,  as  also  below.  M. 


132  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [170-171 

aim  of  this  natural  tendency  is,  to  free  our  notions  from 
the  fetters  of  experience  and  from  the  limits  of  the  mere 
contemplation  of  nature  so  far  as  at  least  to  open  to  us  a 
field,  which  contains  mere  objects  for  the  pure  under 
standing,  which  no  sensibility  can  reach.  [We  do  this] 
not  indeed  with  the  view  of  speculatively  occupying  our 
selves  with  them  (because  we  can  find  no  ground  to  stand 
on),  but,  in  order  that  practical  principles  [may  be  secured], 
which,  with- [171]  out  finding  some  such  scope  for  their 
necessary  expectation  and  hope,  could  not  expand  to  the 
universality,  which  reason  unavoidably  requires  from  the 
moral  point  of  view. 

So  I  find  that  the  Psychological  Idea  (however  little  it  may 
reveal  to  me  the  nature  of  the  human  soul,  which  is  pure 
and  raised  above  all  concepts  of  experience),  yet  shows  the 
insufficiency  of  these  concepts  plainly  enough,  and  thereby 
deters  me  from  materialism,  as  a  notion  unfit  for  any 
explanation  of  nature,  and  besides  confining  reason  [unduly] 
in  the  practical  direction.  The  Cosmological  Ideas,  by  the 
obvious  insufficiency'  of  all  possible  cognition  of  nature  to 
satisfy  reason  in  its  lawful  inquiry,  serve  in  the  same 
manner  to  keep  us  from  naturalism,  which  asserts  nature 
to  be  sufficient  for  itself.  Finally,  all  natural  necessity  in 
the  sensible  world  is  conditional,  as  it  always  presupposes 
the  dependence  of  things  upon  others,  and  unconditional 
necessity  must  be  sought  only  in  the  unity  of  a  cause 
distinguished  from  the  world  of  sense.  But  as  the  causality 
of  this  cause,  in  its  turn,  were  it  merely  nature,  could  never 
render  the  existence  of  the  contingent  (as  its  consequent) 
comprehensible,  Reason  frees  itself  by  means  of  the  Theo 
logical  Idea  from  fatalism  (both  as  a  blind  natural  necessity 
in  the  coherence  of  nature  itself,  without  a  first  principle, 
as  well  as  a  blind  causality  of  this  principle  itself),  and 


171-173]  THE  BOUNDS  OF  PURE  REASON  133 

leads  to  the  concept  of  a  cause  possessing  freedom,  or  of  a 
[172]  Supreme  Intelligence.  Thus  the  transcendental 
Ideas  serve,  if  not  to  instruct  us  positively,  at  least  to 
destroy  the  rash  assertions  of  Materialism,  of  Naturalism, 
and  of  Fatalism,  and  thus  to  afford  scope  for  the  moral 
Ideas  beyond  the  field  of  speculation.  These  considera 
tions,  I  should  think,  explain  in  some  measure  the  natural 
predisposition  of  which  I  spoke. 

The  practical  value,  which  a  merely  speculative  science 
may  have,  lies  without  the  [strict]  bounds  of  this  science, 
and  can  therefore  be  considered  as  a  scholion  merely,  and 
like  all  scholia  does  not  form  part  of  the  science  itself. 
This  application  however  surely  lies  within  the  bounds  of 
philosophy,  especially  'of  philosophy  drawn  from  the  pure 
sources  of  reason,  where  its  speculative  use  in  Metaphysic 
must  necessarily  be  at  unity  with  its  practical  use  in  morals. 
Hence  the  unavoidable  dialectic  of  pure  reason,  considered 
in  Metaphysic  as  a  natural  tendency,  deserves  to  be  ex 
plained  not  as  an  illusion  merely,  which  is  to  be  removed, 
but  also,  if  possible,  as  a  natural  provision  as  regards  its  end, 
though  this  duty,  a  work  of  supererogation,  cannot  justly 
be  assigned  to  Metaphysic  proper. 

The  solutions  of  the  questions  which  occupy  from  page 
410  of  the  Kritik  to  page  432,  should  be  considered  a 
second  scholion,  which  however  has  a  greater  affinity  with 
the  content  of  Metaphysic.  For  there  certain  rational 
principles  are  expounded,  [173]  which  determine  a  priori 
the  order  of  nature  or  rather  of  the  understanding,  which 
seeks  nature's  laws  through  experience.  They  seem  to  be 
constitutive  and  legislative  with  regard  to  experience,  though 
they  spring  from  mere  Reason,  which  cannot  be  considered, 
like  the  understanding,  as  a  principle  of  possible  experience. 
Now  does  this  harmony  rest  upon  the  fact,  that  just  as 


134  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METArHYSIC          [i73'i74 

nature  does  not  inhere  in  phenomena  or  in  their  source  (the 
sensibility)  per  se,  but  only  in  so  far  as  the  latter  is  in 
relation  to  the  understanding,  so  thorough  unity  in  applying 
the  understanding  to  obtain  a  collective  possible  experience 
(in  a  system)  can  only  belong  to  the  understanding  when 
in  relation  to  Reason?  and  is  experience  in  this  way 
mediately  subordinate  to  the  legislation  of  Reason  ?  The 
answer  may  be  discussed  by  those  who  desire  to  trace  the 
nature  of  reason  even  beyond  its  use  in  Metaphysic,  into 
the  general  principles  of  systematising  a  history  of  nature  ; 
I  have  represented  this  problem  as  important,  but  not 
attempted  its  solution,  in  the  book  itself.1 

[174]  And  thus  I  conclude  the  analytical  solution  of 
the  problem  I  had  proposed  :  How  is  metaphysic  in  general 
possible  ?  by  ascending  from  the  facts,  where  the  use  of  the 
science  is  actually  given,  at  least  in  its  consequences,  to  the 
grounds  of  its  possibility. 

1  It  was  my  constant  design  through  the  Kritik  to  neglect  nothing, 
were  it  ever  so  dark,  that  could  complete  the  inquiry  into  the  nature  of 
pure  reason.  Everybody  may  afterwards  carry  his  researches  as  far  as 
he  pleases,  when  he  has  been  merely  shown  what  yet  remains  to  be 
done,  a  duty  reasonably  to  be  expected  from  those  who  have  made  it 
their  business  to  survey  the  whole  of  this  field,  in  order  to  consign  it  to 
others  for  future  allotment  and  cultivation.  And  to  this  branch  both 
the  scholia  belong,  which  will  hardly  recommend  themselves  by  their 
dryness  to  amateurs,  and  hence  are  added  for  competent  judges  only. 


[i7S]  SOLUTION  OF  THE  GENERAL  QUESTION 
OF  THE  PROLEGOMENA 

How  is  Metaphysic  possible  as  a  Science  ? 

METAPHYSIC,  as  a  natural  tendency  of  reason,  is  actual,  but 
when  isolated  (as  the  analytical  solution  of  the  third  principal 
question  showed)  dialectical  and  illusory.  If  we  think  of 
taking  principles  from  it,  and  following  in  their  use  the 
natural,  but  on  that  account  not  less  false,  illusion,  we  can 
therefore  never  produce  science,  but  only  a  vain  dialectical 
art,  in  which  one  school  may  overcome  another,  but  none 
can  ever  acquire  a  just  and  lasting  approbation. 

In  order  that  as  a  science  it  may  claim  not  mere 
fallacious  plausibility,  but  insight  and  conviction,  a  Kritik 
of  the  Reason  must  itself  exhibit  the  whole  stock  of  a  priori 
concepts,  their  division  according  to  their  various  sources 
(Sensibility,  Understanding,  and  Reason),  together  with  a 
complete  table  of  them,  and  the  analysis  of  all  these 
concepts,  with  all  their  consequences. 

It  must  also  exhibit,  especially  by  means  of  the  deduc 
tion  of  these  concepts,  the  possibility  of  [176]  synthetical 
cognition  a  priori,  the  principles  of  its  use,  and  finally 
its  bounds,  all  in  a  complete  system.1  Kritik  therefore, 

1  I  may  note,  as  a  specimen  of  Kant's  style,  that  in  the  original  there 
are  seventy-two  words  in  this  paragraph  between  the  subject  and  the 
verb.  M. 


136  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [176-177 

and  Kritik  alone,  contains  in  itself  the  whole  well  proved 
and  tested  plan,  and  even  all  the  means  required  to  ac 
complish  Metaphysic  as  a  science;  by  other  ways  and 
means  it  is  impossible.  The  question  here  therefore  is  not 
so  much  how  this  performance  is  possible,  as  how  to  set  it 
going,  and  induce  men  of  clear  heads  to  quit  their  hitherto 
perverted  and  fruitless  cultivation  for  one  that  will  not 
deceive,  and  how  such  a  union  for  the  common  end  may 
best  be  directed. 

This  much  is  certain,  that  whoever  has  once  tasted 
Kritik,  will  be  ever  after  disgusted  with  all  dogmatical  slops, 
which  he  formerly  put  up  with,  because  his  reason  must 
have  something,  and  could  find  nothing  better  for  its 
support.  Kritik  stands  in  the  same  relation  to  the  common 
Metaphysic  of  the  schools,  as  chemistry  does  to  alchemy,  or 
as  astronomy  to  prognosticating  astrology.  I  pledge  myself, 
that  nobody  who  has  read  through  and  through,  and  grasped 
the  principles  of,  the  Kritik,  even  in  these  Prolegomena 
only,  will  ever  return  to  that  old  and  sophistical  mock 
science;  but  will  [177]  rather  with  a  certain  delight  look 
forward  to  Metaphysic,  which  is  now  indeed  in  his  power, 
and  requires  no  more  preparatory  discoveries,  and  which 
can  at  last  afford  permanent  satisfaction  to  reason.  For 
here  is  an  advantage  upon  which,  of  all  possible  sciences, 
Metaphysic  alone  can  with  certainty  reckon  :  that  it  can  be 
brought  to  such  completion  and  fixity  as  to  be  incapable  of 
further  change,  or  of  any  augmentation  by  new  discoveries ; 
because  here  reason  has  the  sources  of  its  knowledge  not  in 
objects  and  their  intuition  (by  which  too  it  cannot  be  further 
informed),  but  in  itself.  When  therefore  it  has  exhibited 
the  fundamental  laws  of  its  faculty  completely,  and  so 
determinately  as  to  avoid  all  misunderstanding,  there 
remains  nothing  for  pure  reason  to  cognise  a  priori,  nay, 


177-178]         HOW  IS  METAPHYSIC  POSSIBLE  ?  137 

even  for  it  to  inquire  into  on  [reasonable]  grounds.  The 
sure  prospect  of  knowledge  so  determinate  and  so  self- 
contained1  has  a  peculiar  charm,  even  though  we  should 
set  aside  all  its  advantages,  of  which  I  shall  hereafter  speak. 

All  false  art,  all  vain  wisdom  lasts  its  time,  but  finally 
destroys  itself,  and  its  highest  culture  is  also  the  epoch  of 
its  decay.  That  this  time  is  come  for  Metaphysic  appears 
from  the  state  into  which  it  has  fallen  among  all  learned 
nations,  [178]  despite  of  all  the  zeal  with  which  other 
sciences  of  every  kind  are  prosecuted.  The  old  arrange 
ment  of  our  university  studies  still  preserves  its  shadow ;  a 
single  Academy  of  Sciences  tempts  men  now  and  then,  by 
offering  prizes,  to  write  essays  on  it,  but  it  is  no  longer 
numbered  among  thorough  sciences  ;  and  let  any  one  judge 
for  himself  how  a  man  of  parts,  if  he  were  called  a  great 
metaphysician,  would  receive  the  compliment,  which  may 
be  well-meant,  but  is  scarce  envied  by  anybody. 

Yet,  though  the  period  of  the  downfall  of  all  dogmatical 
metaphysic  has  undoubtedly  arrived,  we  are  yet  far  from 
being  able  to  say,  that  the  period  of  its  regeneration  is  come 
by  means  of  a  thorough  and  complete  Kritik  of  the  Reason. 
All  transitions  from  a  tendency  to  its  contrary  pass  through 
the  stage  of  indifference,  and  this  moment  is  the  most 
dangerous  for  the  author,  but,  in  my  opinion,  the  most 
favourable  for  the  science.  For,  when  party  spirit  has  died 
out  by  a  total  dissolution  of  former  connexions,  minds  are 
in  the  best  state  to  receive,  but  gradually,  proposals  for  a 
combination  according  to  a  new  plan. 

When  I  say,  that  I  hope  these  Prolegomena  will  excite 
investigation  in  the  field  of  Kritik,  and  afford  a  new  and 
promising  object  to  sustain  the  general  spirit  of  philosophy, 

1  This  word  does  not  adequately  render  the  untranslatable  original 
Geschlossenes.     M. 


138  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [178-180 

which  seems  on  its  speculative  side  to  want  sustenance,  I 
can  imagine  [179]  beforehand,  that  every  one,  whom  the 
thorny  paths  of  my  Kritik  have  tired  and  put  out  of 
humour,  will  ask  me,  upon  what  I  found  this  hope  ?  My 
answer  is,  upon  the  irresistible  law  of  necessity. 

That  the  human  mind  will  ever  give  up  metaphysical 
researches  entirely  is  as  little  to  be  expected  as  that  we 
should  prefer  to  give  up  breathing  altogether,  to  avoid  inhaling 
impure  air.  There  will  therefore  always  be  Metaphysic  in 
the  world  ;  nay  every  one,  especially  every  man  of  reflection, 
will  have  it,  and  for  want  of  a  recognised  standard,  will 
shape  it  for  himself  after  his  own  pattern.  What  has 
hitherto  been  called  Metaphysic,  cannot  satisfy  any  accu 
rate  mind,  but  to  forego  it  entirely  is  impossible  \  therefore 
a  Kritik  of  Pure  Reason  itself  must  now  be  attempted  or,  if 
one  exists,  investigated,  and  brought  to  the  full  test,  because 
there  is  no  other  means  of  supplying  this  pressing  want, 
which  is  something  more  than  mere  thirst  for  knowledge. 

Ever  since  I  have  come  to  know  Kritik,  when  I  have 
finished  reading  a  book  of  metaphysical  contents,  which,  by 
the  preciseness  of  its  notions,  by  variety,  order,  and  an 
easy  style,  was  not  only  entertaining  but  improving,  I  cannot 
refrain  from  asking,  Has  this  author  indeed  advanced  Meta 
physic  a  single  step  ?  The  learned  men,  whose  works  have 
been  useful  to  me  in  other  respects  and  always  contributed 
to  the  culture  of  my  mental  pow- [180]  ers,  will,  I  hope, 
forgive  me  for  saying,  that  I  have  never  been  able  to  find  either 
their  essays  or  my  own  less  important  ones  (though  self-love 
may  recommend  them  to  me)  to  have  advanced  the  science 
in  the  least.  And  here  is  the  very  obvious  reason  :  that 
the  science  did  not  then  exist,  and  cannot  be  gathered 
piecemeal,  but  its  germ  must  be  fully  preformed  in  the  Kritik. 
But  in  order  to  prevent  all  misconception,  we  must  remember 


180-181]         HOW  IS  METAPHYSIC  POSSIBLE?  139 

what  has  been  already  said,  that  by  the  analytical  treatment 
of  our  concepts  the  understanding  gains  indeed  a  great  deal, 
but  the  science  (of  metaphysic)  is  not  the  least  advanced, 
because  these  dissections  of  concepts  are  nothing  but  the 
materials  from  which  the  science  still  remains  to  be  built. 
Let  the  concepts  of  substance  and  of  accident  be  ever  so 
well  dissected  and  determined,  all  this  is  very  well  as  a 
preparation  for  some  future  use.  But  if  we  cannot  prove, 
that  in  all  which  exists  the  substance  endures,  and  only  the 
accidents  vary,  science  is  not  the  least  advanced  by  all 
our  analyses.  Metaphysic  has  hitherto  never  been  able  to 
prove  a  priori  either  this  proposition,  or  that  of  Sufficient 
Reason,  still  less  any  more  complex  one,  such  as  belongs 
to  [rational]  psychology  or  cosmology,  or  indeed  any  syn 
thetical  proposition.  By  all  its  analysis  therefore  nothing 
is  affected,  nothing  obtained  or  forwarded,  and  the  science, 
after  all  this  bustle  and  noise,  still  remains  as  it  was  in  the 
[181]  days  of  Aristotle,  though  far  better  preparations  were 
made  for  it  than  of  old,  if  the  clue  to  synthetical  cognitions 
had  only  been  discovered. 

If  any  one  thinks  himself  insulted,  he  may  easily  refute 
my  charge  by  producing  a  single  synthetical  proposition 
belonging  to  Metaphysic,  which  he  proposes  to  prove 
dogmatically  a  priori,  for  until  he  has  performed  this  feat, 
I  shall  not  grant  that  he  has  actually  advanced  the  science ; 
even  should  that  proposition  be  sufficiently  confirmed  by 
common  experience.  No  demand  can  be  more  moderate 
or  more  equitable,  and  in  the  (infallibly  certain)  event  of 
its  non- performance,  no  assertion  more  just,  than  that 
hitherto  Metaphysic  has  never  existed  as  a  science. 

But  there  are  two  things  which,  in  case  the  challenge  be 
accepted,  I  must  deprecate :  first,  trifling  about  probability 
and  conjecture,  which  are  suited  as  little  to  metaphysic,  as 


140  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [181-182 

to  geometry ;  and  secondly,  the  decision  by  means  of  the 
wand  of  sound  common  sense,  which  every  one  does  not 
wave,  but  which  accommodates  itself  to  personal  peculiarities. 

For  as  to  the  former,  nothing  can  be  more  absurd,  than 
in  Metaphysic,  a  philosophy  from  pure  reason,  to  think  of 
grounding  our  judgments  upon  probability  and  conjecture. 
Everything  that  is  to  be  cognised  a  priori,  is  thereby 
announced  as  apodeictically  certain,  and  must  therefore  be 
proved  [182]  in  this  way.  We  might  as  well  think  of 
grounding  geometry  or  arithmetic  upon  conjectures  ;  for  as 
to  the  doctrine  of  chances  in  the  latter,  it  does  not  contain 
probable,  but  perfectly  certain  judgments  concerning  the 
degree  of  the  probability  of  certain  cases,  under  given  uni 
form  conditions,  which,  in  the  sum  of  all  possible  cases, 
infallibly  happen  according  to  the  rule,  though  it  is  not 
sufficiently  determined  in  respect  to  every  single  chance. 
Conjectures  (by  means  of  induction  and  of  analogy)  can  be 
suffered  in  an  empirical  science  of  nature  only,  yet  even 
there  the  possibility  at  least  of  what  we  assume  must  be 
quite  certain. 

The  appeal  to  sound  sense  is  even  more  absurd,  when 
concepts  and  principles  are  announced  as  valid,  not  in  so 
far  as  they  hold  with  regard  to  experience,  but  even  beyond 
the  conditions  of  experience.  For  what  is  sound  sense 
[Verstand]  ?  It  is  common  sense,  so  far  as  it  judges  right. 
But  what  is  common  sense  ?  It  is  the  faculty  of  the  know 
ledge  and  use  of  rules  in  concreto,  as  distinguished  from  the 
speculative  understanding,  which  is  a  faculty  of  knowing  rules 
in  abstracto.  Common  sense  can  hardly  understand  the 
rule,  '  that  every  event  is  determined  by  means  of  its  cause,' 
and  can  never  comprehend  it  thus  generally.  It  therefore 
demands  an  example  from  experience,  and  when  it  hears 
that  this  rule  means  nothing  but  what  it  always  thought 


182-184]         HOW  IS  METAPHYSIC  POSSIBLE  ?  141 

when  a  pane  was  [183]  broken  or  a  kitchen-utensil  missing, 
it  then  understands  the  principle  and  grants  it.  Common 
sense  therefore  is  only  of  use  so  far  as  it  can  see  its  rules 
(though  actually  present  in  it  a  priori]  confirmed  by  ex 
perience  ;  consequently  to  comprehend  them  a  priori,  or 
independently  of  experience,  belongs  to  the  speculative 
understanding,  and  lies  quite  beyond  the  horizon  of  common 
sense.  But  the  province  of  Metaphysic  is  entirely  confined 
to  the  latter  kind  of  knowledge,  and  it  is  certainly  a  bad 
index  of  sound  sense  to  appeal  to  the  witness,  which  cannot 
here  form  any  opinion  whatever,  and  on  which  men  look 
down  with  contempt  until  they  are  in  difficulties,  and  can 
find  in  their  speculation  neither  counsel  nor  help. 

It  is  a  common  subterfuge  of  those  false  friends  of 
common  sense  (who  occasionally  prize  it  highly,  but  usually 
despise  it)  to  say,  that  there  must  surely  be  at  all  events 
some  propositions,  which  are  immediately  certain,  and  of 
which  there  is  no  occasion  to  give  any  proof,  or  even  any 
account  at  all,  because  we  otherwise  could  never  stop  in 
quiring  into  the  grounds  of  our  judgments.1  But  if  we  ex 
cept  the  principle  of  contradiction,  which  is  not  sufficient  to 
show  the  truth  of  synthetical  judgments,  they  can  never 
adduce,  in  proof  of  this  privilege,  anything  [184]  else  in 
dubitable,  which  they  can  immediately  ascribe  to  common 
sense,  except  mathematical  propositions,  such  as  twice  two 
make  four,  between  two  points  there  is  but  one  straight  line, 
etc.  But  these  are  judgments  immensely  distinct  from  those 
of  Metaphysic.  For  in  Mathematic  I  myself  can  by  thinking 
make  (construct)  whatever  I  represent  to  myself  as  possible 
by  a  concept :  I  add  to  the  first  two  the  other  two,  one  by 
one,  and  myself  make  the  number  four,  or  I  draw  in  thought 

1  These  remarks  are  probably  written  with  the  Scottish  School  in 
view.     M. 


I42  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC          [184-185 

from  one  point  to  another  all  manner  of  lines,  and  can  draw 
one  only,  which  is  like  itself  in  all  its  parts  (equal  as  well  as 
unequal).  But  I  cannot,  by  all  my  power  of  thinking, 
extract  from  the  concept  of  a  thing  the  concept  of  something 
else,  whose  existence  is  necessarily  connected  with  the  former, 
but  must  call  in  experience.  And  though  my  understanding 
furnishes  me  a  priori  (yet  only  in -reference  to  possible  ex 
perience)  with  the  concept  of  such  a  connexion  (of  causation), 
I  cannot  exhibit  it,  like  the  concepts  of  mathematic,  by  in 
tuition,  a  priori^  and  so  show  its  possibility  a  priori.  So 
this  concept,  together  with  the  principles  of  its  application, 
always  requires,  if  it  shall  hold  a  priori — as  is  requisite  in 
Metaphysic — a  justification  and  deduction  of  its  possibility, 
because  we  cannot  otherwise  know  how  far  it  holds  good, 
and  whether  it  can  be  used  in  experience  only  or  beyond  it 
also.  In  Metaphysic,  then,  as  a  speculative  science  of  pure 
reason,  we  [185]  can  never  appeal  to  common  sense,  but 
may  only  do  so  when  we  are  forced  to  quit  it,  and  to  give 
up  all  pure  speculative  cognition  (which  must  always  be 
science),  and  consequently  [to  give  up]  metaphysic  itself, 
and  its  instruction.  [This  may  happen]  on  certain  occasions, 
when  a  reasonable  faith  only  is  found  possible  for  us,  and 
sufficient  to  our  wants  (perhaps  even  more  salutary  than 
science  itself).  For  in  this  case  the  attitude  of  the  question 
is  quite  altered.  Metaphysic  must  be  science  not  only  as  a 
whole,  but  in  all  its  parts,  otherwise  it  is  nothing ;  because, 
as  a  speculation  of  pure  reason,  it  has  a  footing  nowhere  else 
than  on  general  views.  Beyond  it,  however,  probability  and 
sound  sense  may  be  used  with  advantage  and  justly,  but  on 
quite  special  principles,  of  which  the  importance  always  de 
pends  on  the  reference  to  practice. 

This  is  what  I  hold  myself  justified  in  requiring  for  the 
possibility  of  Metaphysic  as  a  science. 


[i86]  APPENDIX 

On  what  can  be  done  to  make  Metapkysic  actual  as  a  Science 

As  no  means  hitherto  used  have  attained  this  end,  which 
without  a  preceding  Kritik  of  pure  reason  will  never  be 
attained,  it  is  fair  to  expect  that  the  essay,  which  is  now  be 
fore  the  public,  should  be  submitted  to  an  accurate  and 
careful  scrutiny,  except  it  be  thought  more  advisable  to  give 
up  all  pretensions  to  Metaphysic,  in  which  case,  if  men  but 
adhere  to  their  purpose,  nothing  can  be  said  against  it.  If 
we  take  the  course  of  things  as  it  is,  not  as  it  ought  to  be, 
there  are  two  sorts  of  judgments,  one  a  judgment  which  pre 
cedes  investigation — in  our  case  one  in  which  the  reader  from 
his  own  Metaphysic  pronounces  judgment  on  the  Kritik  of 
Pure  Reason  (which  was  intended  to  discuss  the  very 
possibility  of  Metaphysic).  The  other  is  a  judgment  sub 
sequent  to  investigation,  in  which  the  reader  is  enabled  to 
waive  for  awhile  the  consequences  of  the  critical  researches 
that  may  be  repugnant  to  his  formerly  adopted  Metaphysic, 
and  first  examines  the  grounds  whence  those  consequences 
are  derived.  If  what  common  Metaphysic  propounds  were 
[187]  demonstrably  certain  (like  geometry,  for  instance), 
the  former  way  of  judging  would  hold  good ;  for  if  the  con 
sequences  of  certain  principles  are  repugnant  to  established 
truths,  these  principles  are  false,  and  without  further  inquiry 


144  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC  [187 

to  be  repudiated.  But  if  Metaphysic  does  not  possess  a 
stock  of  indisputably  certain  (synthetical)  propositions,  and 
should  it  even  be  the  case  that  there  are  a  number  of  them, 
which,  though  among  the  most  specious,  are  by  their  con 
sequences  in  mutual  collision,  and  if  no  sure  criterion  of  the 
truth  of  peculiarly  metaphysical  (synthetical)  propositions  is 
to  be  met  with  in  it,  then  the  former  way  of  judging  cannot 
obtain,  but  the  investigation  of  the  principles  of  the  Kritik 
must  precede  all  judgment  as  to  its  value. 


SPECIMEN  OF  A  JUDGMENT  ON  THE  KRITIK 
PRIOR  TO  ITS  EXAMINATION 

Such  may  be  found  in  the  Gbttingen  gelehrte  Anz.  (iQth  Jan.  1782). 

WHEN  an  author  who  understands  his  work,  and  has 
taken  care  to  think  it  out  independently,  falls  into  the 
hands  of  a  reviewer  acute  enough  to  perceive  the  points 
of  real  moment  in  determining  the  merit  or  demerit  of  the 
book,  who  attends  not  to  the  words  but  to  the  matter,  and 
does  not  merely  weigh  the  principles  from  which  the  author 
started — in  such  case  the  latter  may  dislike  his  verdict, 
but  the  public,  who  only  gains  by  it,  need  not  care  :  and 
even  the  author  may  be  content  to  take  the  opportunity  of 
reconsidering  the  positions  criticised  in  good  time  by  a 
good  authority,  and  thus,  should  the  objections  be  well 
grounded,  of  removing  any  rock  of  offence  which  might 
damage  the  work. 

This  is  not  my  present  position.  My  critic  does  not 
seem  to  have  an  inkling  of  what  my  inquiry  (successful  or 
not)  aimed  at  attaining.  It  may  be  want  of  patience  to 
toil  through  a  voluminous  book,  or  annoyance  at  a  proposed 
reform  in  a  science  concerning  which  he  had  long  since 
satisfied  himself,  or  (what  I  do  not  willingly  surmise)  a 
narrow  view  which  cannot  rise  above  the  ordinary  meta- 
physic  of  the  schools.  Whatever  the  cause,  he  goes 

II  L 


146  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC 

through  a  long  row  of  propositions,  which  nobody -would 
understand  without  the  premises  leading  up  to  them, 
dispenses  here  and  there  his  censure,  which  is  as  incompre 
hensible  as  the  statements  censured,  and  so  neither  profits 
the  public  by  information,  nor  damages  me  the  least  in  the 
minds  of  experts.  I  should  therefore  have  passed  it  by 
in  silence,  except  that  it  gives  me  the  opportunity  of  ex 
planations  which  may  save  the  readers  of  my  Prolegomena 
from  some  possible  mistakes. 

In  order  to  take  up  a  position  from  which  he  could  give 
an  unfavourable  view  of  the  whole  book,  without  con 
descending  to  any  particular  inquiry,  the  reviewer  begins 
and  ends  with  saying,  "  this  work  is  a  system  of  transcend 
ent  (or  as  he  translates  it,  of  higher)1  idealism.  A  glance 
at  this  statement  told  me  what  I  might  expect — something 
like  as  if  a  man  who  had  never  heard  of  geometry  had 
suddenly  found  a  Euclid,  and  being  asked  to  review  it, 
were  to  turn  over  the  leaves  and  find  many  figures,  and  then 
say :  "  The  book  is  a  systematic  lesson-book  in  drawing ; 
but  the  author  uses  a  peculiar  language  to  give  dark  and 
obscure  precepts,  which  after  all  can  do  no  more  than  any 
one  can  attain  with  a  good  eye,  etc." 

But  let  us  see  what  sort  of  idealism  runs  through  my 


1  By  no  means  higher.  High  towers,  and  their  human  rivals  in 
metaphysic,  both  with  so  much  wind  about  them,  are  not  in  my  line. 
My  place  is  the  fruitful  low  ground  [bathos]  of  experience ;  and  'the 
word  transcendental,  whose  repeated  explanation  in  my  book  he  has 
never  even  grasped — so  hurriedly  did  he  read  me — does  not  mean  any 
thing  transcending  all  experience,  but  its  a  priori  condition,  with  no 
other  purpose  than  to  make  empirical  cognition  merely  possible.  When 
these  concepts  transcend  experience,  their  employment  becomes  tran 
scendent,  which  is  distinguished  from  their  immanent  use  confined  to 
experience.  All  this  I  had  carefully  guarded  against  ;  but  the  reviewer 
found  it  his  advantage  to  misunderstand  me. 


SUPPLEMENT 


whole  work,  though  it  is  far  from  being  the  soul  of  my 
system. 

The  position  of  all  genuine  idealists  from  the  Eleatics 
to  Berkeley  is  this  :  All  cognition  through  the  senses  and 
experience  is  nothing  but  mere  illusion,  and  only  in  the 
ideas  of  the  pure  Understanding  and  the  Reason  is  there 
truth.  The  fundamental  principle  ruling  all  my  idealism, 
on  the  contrary,  is  this:  All  cognition  of  things  from 
mere  pure  Understanding  and  Reason  is  nothing  but  mere 
illusion  and  only  in  experience  is  there  truth. 

But  this  is  the  very  opposite  of  that  other  proper 
idealism.  How  did  I  come  to  use  this  term  for  a  directly 
opposite  purpose,  and  how  did  the  reviewer  come  to  see 
it  everywhere  ? 

The  solution  of  this  difficulty  depends  upon  something 
easy  to  take  out  of  the  connected  work,  if  you  choose  to  do 
it.  Space  and  time,  with  all  that  they  contain,  are  not 
things  or  their  properties  per  se,  but  belong  to  the  pheno 
mena  of  things.  So  far  I  agree  with  every  idealist.  But 
these,  especially  Berkeley,  regarded  space  as  a  mere 
empirical  representation,  which  along  with  all  its  determina 
tions  is  known,  like  what  appears  in  it,  only  through 
experience  or  perception.  I  was  the  first  to  show  that 
space  (and  time,  which  Berkeley  overlooked)  with  all  its 
determinations  is  known  by  us  a  priori,  because  it  and 
time  are  in  us  as  pure  forms  of  sensibility  before  all 
perception  or  experience,  and  make  all  intuition  and  con 
sequently  all  phenomena  possible.  Hence  it  follows  that 
as  truth  rests  on  universal  and  necessary  laws  as  its  criteria, 
experience  can  have  in  Berkeley's  system  no  criteria  of 
truth,  because  there  is  nothing  a  priori  at  the  basis  of  its 
phenomena;  and  further  it  follows  that  all  experience  is 
mere  illusion,  whereas  with  me  space  and  time  (in  con- 


148  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC 

nection  with  the  Categories)  prescribe  a  priori  the  law 
of  all  possible  experience,  and  this  law  gives  us  the  sure 
criterion  for  distinguishing  truth  from  illusion.1  My  so- 
called  (critical)  idealism  is  thus  quite  peculiar,  in  that  it 
overthrows  ordinary  idealism,  and  that  through  it  all  a 
priori  cognition,  even  that  of  geometry,  now  attains  objective 
reality,  a  thing  which  even  the  keenest  realist  could  not 
assert  till  I  had  proved  the  ideality  of  space  and  time.  I 
wish  I  could  call  this  attitude  of  mine  by  some  other  name, 
to  avoid  all  such  misapprehensions,  but  a  complete  change 
seems  to  me  impracticable.  I  may  therefore  in  future  be 
allowed  to  call  it,  as  above  explained,  formal,  or  rather 
critical,  idealism,  to  distinguish  it  from  the  dogmatic  of 
Berkeley,  and  the  sceptical  of  Descartes. 

I  find  nothing  further  of  note  in  this  estimate  of  my 
book.2  The  critic  deals  throughout  in  broad  generalities — 
a  wise  course,  because  the  writer  does  not  betray  the 
amount  of  his  own  knowledge  or  ignorance ;  a  single 
criticism  in  detail,  affecting,  as  it  ought,  the  main  questions 
of  the  book,  would  have  exposed  perhaps  my  error, 
perhaps  also  the  amount  of  insight  the  reviewer  possessed 
into  questions  of  this  kind.  It  was  no  bad  device,  for  the 
purpose  of  deterring  at  once  readers  accustomed  to  rely  on 
reviews  for  their  opinion  of  books,  to  enumerate  a  number 
of  statements,  which  must  necessarily  have  seemed  absurd 

1  Idealism  proper  has  always,  and  necessarily,  a  mystical  tendency, 
but  mine  only  aims  at  comprehending  the  possibility  of  knowing  the 
things  of  experience  a  priori — a  problem  never  solved,  nay,  never 
even  proposed.  This  disposes  of  mystical  idealism,  which  (as  Plato 
shows)  infers  from  our  a  priori  cognitions  (even  in  geometry) 
another  (viz.  intellectual)  intuition,  differing  from  that  of  the  senses, 
because  no  one  dreamt  that  the  senses  could  have  any  a  priori 
intuition. 

'  Not  the  judgment  of  the  book  in  question,'  as  Mr.  Bax  translates, 
evidently  supposing  it  to  be  some  work  of  Garve.     M. 


SUPPLEMENT  149 


when  torn  from  their  connection  with  proofs  and  explana 
tions,  and  which,  moreover,  conflict  violently  with  current 
metaphysic.  So  the  reader's  patience  is  disgusted,  and 
then,  after  I  am  taught  the  profound  statement,  that  per 
sistent  illusion  is  truth — then  comes  the  blunt  patronising 
conclusion  :  Why  this  attack  on  the  received  use  of  words  ; 
wherefore  this  idealistic  distinction  ?  This  judgment, 
which  began  with  making  metaphysical  heresies  the  main 
point  of  my  book,  ends  by  reducing  it  to  mere  innovations 
of  language,  and  shows  clearly  that  my  would-be  judge 
knows  nothing  about  the  subject,  and  even  misunderstands 
his  own  arguments.1 

The  reviewer  talks  like  a  man  possessed  of  important 
news,  which  he  keeps  concealed  from  the  public,  though  I 
know  of  nothing  which  has  lately  appeared  in  metaphysics 
to  warrant  such  an  attitude.  It  is  very  wrong  of  him  to 
withhold  his  discoveries  for  ...  the  world  is  tired  of 
metaphysical  assertions ;  what  we  want  is  a  proof  of  the 
possibility  of  this  science,  and  safe  criteria  to  distinguish 
the  dialectical  illusion  of  the  pure  reason  from  truth.  I 
suspect  that  this  requirement  has  never  even  come  into  his 
head,  and  .  .  .  support  my  suspicions  by  the  fact  that  he 
is  absolutely  silent  concerning  the  possibility  of  synthetic 
a  priori  knowledge,  which  is  the  special  problem  in  the 
way  of  metaphysic,  and  to  which  my  Kritik  and  Prolegomena 

1  The  reviewer  often  fights  with  his  own  shadow.  When  I  oppose 
the  truth  of  experience  to  dreaming,  he  never  suspects  that  I  am  only 
concerned  with  the  somni-um  objective  sumtum  of  Wolffs  philosophy, 
which  is  merely  formal,  and  does  not  regard  the  distinction  of  dreaming 
and  waking,  which  indeed  has  no  place  in  any  transcendental  philosophy. 
Again  he  calls  my  Deduction  of  the  Categories  and  Table  of  the 
Principles  of  the  Understanding  'current  principles  of  Logic  and  Ontology 
idealistically  expressed.'  The  reader  need  only  consult  these  Pro 
legomena^  to  persuade  himself,  that  such  a  criticism  was  the  most 
miserable  and  even  historically  false  which  a  man  could  make. 


1 5o  PROLEGOMENA  TO  METAPHYSIC 

were  mainly  directed.  The  idealism  at  which  he  caught, 
and  to  which  he  stuck,  was  only  embraced  by  me  as  the 
one  means  of  solving  that  problem  (though  it  may  be  con 
firmed  from  other  grounds),  and  he  should  have  shown, 
either  that  the  problem  does  not  possess  the  importance  I 
attached  to  it,  both  in  Kritik  and  Prolegomena,  or  that  it 
cannot  be  solved  by  my  view  of  phenomena,  or  else  be 
solved  better  in  some  other  way.  .  .  .  Other  sciences 
have  their  touchstone.1  But  to  judge  the  thing  called 
metaphysic,  we  must  first  discover  that  touchstone,  which 
I  have  attempted,  as  well  as  to  apply  its  use.  ...  To 
bring  my  defence  to  a  point,  I  here  make  an  offer,  like 
those  often  made  by  the  mathematicians,  to  prove  by  com 
petition  the  superiority  of  their  respective  methods.  I 
challenge  my  opponent  to  prove,  of  course  a  priori,  a 
single  one  of  the  propositions  asserted  by  him  to  be  really 
metaphysical,  i.e.  synthetical  a  priori,  such  as  the  principle 
of  the  permanence  of  substance,  or  the  necessary  deter 
mination  of  events  by  their  causes.  If  he  fails  in  doing 
this,  he  must  admit  that  as  metaphysic  is  nothing  at  all 
without  the  demonstrated  certainty  of  such  propositions, 
the  possibility  or  impossibility  of  the  science  is  the  first 
task  of  a  Kritik  of  pure  reason  ;  either,  then,  he  must  confess 
that  my  principles  are  sound,  or  he  must  refute  them.  .  .  . 
So  sure  am  I  of  his  failure  in  any  such  attempt,  that  I  will 
even  give  him  the  advantage  of  taking  the  onus  probandi 
on  myself. 

Here  is  my  challenge.  He  finds  in  these  Prolegomena 
and  Kritik  eight  pieces  of  contradictory  propositions  (the 
Theses  and  Antitheses  of  the  four  Antinomies),  each  of 

1  From  this  on  I  have  only  given  the  philosophical  points  in 
Kant's  argument,  the  personal  allusions  are  now  devoid  of  interest 
to  the  philosophical  reader.  M. 


SUPPLEMENT 


which  belongs  necessarily  to  metaphysic,  which  must 
either  accept  or  refute  it  (though  there  is  probably  not  a 
single  one  of  them  which  has  not  in  its  turn  been  assumed 
by  some  philosopher).  He  is  at  liberty  to  accept  any  one 
of  these  eight,  and  adopt  it  with  the  proof,  which  I  give 
him  into  the  bargain,  and  then  let  him  attack  my  proof  of 
the  contrary  proposition.  If  I  can  protect  this  latter,  and 
show  on  principles  indispensable  to  every  dogmatical 
metaphysic  that  the  opposite  of  his  position  can  be  just  as 
clearly  maintained,  then  there  must  be  a  radical  error  in 
metaphysic  not  to  be  explained  or  removed  without  going 
back  to  the  birthplace  of  metaphysic  in  the  pure  reason ; 
so  that  either  my  Kritik  must  be  adopted  or  a  better 
supplied  in  its  place. 

If  I  am  not  able  to  maintain  my  proof,  then  my  opponent 
has  made  good  at  least  one  synthetical  a  priori  pro 
position  on  dogmatical  grounds ;  my  attack  on  popular 
metaphysic  was  unwarranted,  and  I  bow  to  his  censure. 


APPENDICES 

CONTAINING 

TRANSLATIONS   OF  THE   PRINCIPAL   PASSAGES   IN  THE   KRIT1K 

OF  THE  PURE  REASON  ALTERED  IN  THE  SECOND  (AND 

FOLLOWING)   EDITIONS,    AND    OF    PART    OF 

THE  CRITICAL  SOLUTION   OF  THE 

THIRD    ANTINOMY 


A.  ON  THE  DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES 

B.  ON  THE  DISTINCTION  BETWEEN  NOUMENA  AND  PHENO 

MENA 

C.  ON  THE  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

D.  ON  THE  INTELLIGIBLE  AND  THE  EMPIRICAL  CHARACTER 


APPENDIX    A 


DEDUCTION   OF  THE   PURE  CONCEPTS   OF 
THE   UNDERSTANDING 

§  2.  Of  the  a  priori  Grounds  of  the  Possibility  of  Experience 

THAT  a  concept  should  be  generated  completely  a  priori, 
and  have  relation  to  an  object,  without  itself  belonging  to 
the  [general]  notion  of  possible  experience,  or  being  made 
up  of  the  elements  of  possible  experience  1  —  this  is  perfectly 
self-  contradictory  and  impossible.  For  such  a  concept 
would  have  no  content,  because  no  intuition  would  cor 
respond  to  it  ;  since  intuitions  in  genera],  by  which  objects 
are  capable  of  being  given  to  us,  make  up  the  field,  or 
total  object,  of  possible  experience.  A  concept  a  priori, 
which  did  not  refer  to  such  intuitions,  would  be  only  the 
logical  form  for  a  concept,  but  not  the  very  concept  itself, 
through  which  something  is  thought. 

If  there  be  then  pure  concepts  a  priori,  these  indeed 
can  of  course  contain  nothing  empirical  ;  they  must,  never 
theless,  be  merely  a  priori  conditions  of  possible  [192]  ex 
perience,  as  upon  this  alone  can  their  objective  reality  rest. 

1  By  possible  experience  Kant  means  that  which  can  possibly  become 
experience.     M. 


iS6  APPENDIX  A  [192-193 

If  we  wish,  then,  to  know  how  pure  concepts  of  the 
understanding  are  possible,  we  must  inquire  what  are  the 
a  priori  conditions  on  which  the  possibility  of  experience 
depends,  and  which  form  its  foundation,  when  we  abstract 
from  all  that  is  empirical  in  phenomena.  A  concept  which 
expresses  this  formal  and  objective  condition  of  experience 
universally  and  adequately  might  be  denominated  a  pure 
concept  of  the  understanding.  Having  once  obtained  pure 
concepts  of  the  understanding,  I  can,  if  I  like,  also 
excogitate  objects,  perhaps  impossible,  perhaps  possible /^ 
se,  but  given  in  no  experience ;  since  I  may  omit  in  the 
connexion  of  these  concepts  something  which  still  neces 
sarily  belongs  to  the  conditions  of  possible  experience  (e.g. 
the  notion  of  a  spirit) ;  or  else  I  may  extend  pure  concepts 
of  the  understanding  further  than  experience  can  reach  (e.g. 
the  notion  of  the  Deity).  But  the  elements  of  all  a  priori 
cognitions,  even  those  of  capricious  and  absurd  chimeras, 
cannot  indeed  be  borrowed  from  experience  (or  they  would 
not  be  a  priori  cognitions),  but  must  in  every  case  contain 
the  pure  a  priori  conditions  of  possible  experience,  and  of 
an  object  thereof;  otherwise  we  should  not  only  be  thinking 
nothing  by  means  of  such  chimeras,  but  they  themselves, 
having  no  starting-point,  could  not  even  originate  in 
thought. 

Now  these  concepts,  which  contain  a  priori  the  pure 
thinking  in  each  individual  experience,  we  find  in  the 
Categories  ;  and  it  will  be  a  sufficient  deduction  of  them, 
and  a  justification  of  their  objective  validity,  if  we  prove 
that  through  them  alone  can  an  object  be  thought.  But, 
as  in  such  a  thought  there  is  more  than  the  mere  faculty 
[193]  of  thinking — that  is,  the  understanding — concerned; 
and  as  this  faculty,  considered  as  a  cognitive  faculty,  which 
must  relate  to  objects,  will  also  require  some  explanation, 


193-194]        DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES 


157 


with  regard  to  the  possibility  of  such  relation  ; — we  must, 
accordingly,  first  discuss  the  subjective  sources1  which 
constitute  the  a  priori  foundation  of  the  possibility  of 
experience,  not  according  to  their  empirical,  but  according 
to  their  transcendental,  nature. 

If  each  individual  representation  were  quite  estranged 
from  the  rest,  so  as  to  be  as  it  were  isolated  and  separated 
from  them,  such  a  thing  as  knowledge  never  could  come 
into  existence ;  for  knowledge  means  a  totality  of  compared  1 
and  connected  representations.  If  then  I  add  to  sense,  ( 
because  it  contains  multiplicity  in  its  intuition,  a  synopsis, 
to  this  synopsis  must  correspond  in  every  case  a  synthesis ; 
and  it  is  only  when  combined  with  spontaneity  that  re 
ceptivity  can  make  cognitions  possible.  This  spontaneity, 
then,  is  the  foundation  of  a  threefold  synthesis,  which 
necessarily  occurs  in  all  knowledge  :  first,  the  apprehension 
of  representations,  as  modifications  of  the  mind  in  intuition  ; 
secondly,  the  reproduction  of  them  in  the  imagination  ;  and, 
thirdly,  their  recognition  in  the  concept.  These  point  to 
three  subjective  sources  of  cognition  which  render  possible 
the  understanding  itself,  and  through  it  experience  also,  as 
an  empirical  product  of  the  understanding. 


[194]  PREFATORY  REMARK 

The  deduction  of  the  Categories  is  involved  in  such 
difficulties,  and  compels  us  to  penetrate  so  deeply  into  the 
original  causes  and  conditions  of  the  possibility  of  our 
knowledge  in  general,  that  in  order  to  avoid  the  diffuseness 
of  a  complete  theory,  and  at  the  same  time  to  omit  nothing 

1  This  is  the  aspect  omitted  in  the  Second  Edition,  and  alluded  to 
in  the  first  Preface.     Cf.  vol.  i.  p.  5.     M. 


158  APPENDIX  A  [i94'i95 

in  so  necessary  an  investigation,  I  have  thought  it  better,  in 
the  four  following  paragraphs,  rather  to  prepare  than  in 
struct  the  reader,  and  not  to  lay  before  him  the  systematic 
discussion  of  these  elements  of  the  understanding  till  the 
succeeding  third  section.  I  hope  the  reader  will  not  permit 
the  obscurity  he  at  first  meets  to  deter  him,  as  such  obscurity 
is  unavoidable  on  entering  upon  a  wholly  untrodden  path, 
but  will,  I  hope,  be  perfectly  removed  in  the  section  to 
which  I  have  referred. 

i.  Of  the  Synthesis  of  Apprehension  in  Intuition. — From 
whatsoever  source  our  representations  arise — whether 
through  the  influence  of  external  things,  or  from  internal 
causes l — whether  they  originate  a  priori,  or  empirically, 
they  must  nevertheless  belong  as  phenomena  (being  modifica 
tions  of  our  minds)  to  the  internal  sense ;  and,  as  such,  all 
our  cognitions  must  ultimately  be  subject  to  the  formal 
condition  of  our  internal  sense — Time — as  being  that  in 
which  they  are  all  ordered,  connected,  and  brought  into 
relation.  This  general  remark  must  be  above  all  things 
kept  carefully  in  view  throughout  the  following  discussion. 

Every  intuition  contains  in  itself  a  multiplicity,  which 
nevertheless  would  not  be  represented  as  such,  if  the  [195] 
mind  did  not  distinguish  time  in  the  sequence  of  im 
pressions  one  upon  another ;  for,  so  far  as  it  is  contained 
in  a  single  instant,  no  representation  could  ever  be  anything 
but  an  absolute  unity.  In  order,  then,  to  make  out  of  this 
manifold  a  unity  of  intuition  (as,  for  example,  in  the 
representation  of  space),2  it  is  in  the  first  instance  necessary 

1  This  looks  very  like  a  suggestion  of  Realism  in  the  First  Edi 
tion.     M 

2  The  reader  should  here  notice  the  element  omitted  (for  the  sake  of 
simplicity)  in  Kant's  Aesthetic,  and   to  which  he  afterwards  refers, 
Kritik,  p.  98,  note.     M. 


195-196]        DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  159 

to  run  through  the  multiplicity,  and  then  grasp  it  together 
— an  action  which  I  call  synthesis  of  apprehension,  as  being 
directed  immediately  towards  intuition,  which  indeed  pre 
sents  to  us  multiplicity,  but  which  without  a  simultaneous 
synthesis  cannot  produce  it  as  such,  and  also  as  contained 
in  one  representation. 

Now  this  synthesis  of  apprehension  must  also  be  carried 
out  a  priori^  that  is  to  say,  in  the  case  of  representations 
which  are  not  empirical.  For  without  it  we  could  not  have 
representations  either  of  space  or  time  a  priori,  as  these 
can  only  be  generated  by  means  of  the  synthesis  of  the 
manifold,  which  [manifold]  the  sensibility  offers  in  its 
original  receptivity.  We  have  then  a  pure  synthesis  of 
apprehension. 

2.  Of  the  Synthesis  of  Reproduction  in  the  Imagination. — 
It  is  indeed  only  an  empirical  law,  according  to  which 
representations  which  have  often  accompanied  or  followed 
one  another  at  length  become  associated,  and  so  form  a 
connexion,  according  to  which,  even  in  the  absence  of  the 
object,  one  of  these  representations  produces  a  transition  of 
the  mind  to  another,  by  a  fixed  rule.  But  this  law  of 
reproduction  presupposes  that  phenomena  themselves  are 
actually  subject  to  such  a  rule,  [196]  and  that  in  the 
multiplicity  of  their  representations  there  is  a  concomitance 
or  sequence,  according  to  a  fixed  rule;  for  otherwise  our 
empirical  imagination  would  never  find  anything  to  do 
suited  to  its  nature,  and  would  consequently  remain  hidden 
within  the  depths  of  the  mind  as  a  torpid  faculty,  not 
even  known  to  ourselves.  Supposing  vermilion  were  at  one 
time  red,  at  another  black — at  one  time  heavy,  at  another 
light ;  were  a  man  changed  first  into  one,  then  into  another 
animal — were  our  fields  covered  on  the  longest  day,  at  one 
time  with  corn,  at  another  with  ice  and  snow — then  my 


i6o  APPENDIX  A  [196-197 

empirical  faculty  of  imagination  would  never  have  had  even 
the  opportunity  of  thinking  of  the  heavy  vermilion,  when 
red  colour  was  presented  to  it ;  or  again,  were  a  certain 
word  applied  first  to  one  thing,  then  to  another,  or  the 
same  thing  called  by  different  names,  without  the  control 
of  a  fixed  law,  to  which  the  phenomena  are  already 
themselves  subject,  there  could  be  no  empirical  synthesis 
of  reproduction. 

There  must,  then,  be  something  which  makes  even  the 
reproduction  of  phenomena  possible,  by  being  the  a  priori 
foundation  of  a  necessary  synthetical  unity  among  them. 
But  we  very  soon  hit  upon  it  when  we  reflect  that  pheno 
mena  are  not  things  in  themselves,  but  the  mere  play  of 
our  representations,  which  are,  after  all,  only  determinations 
of  our  internal  sense.  For  if  we  can  make  it  plain  that 
even  our  purest  a  priori  intuitions  afford  us  no  knowledge, 
except  so  far  as  they  contain  a  combination  of  multiplicity 
only  to  be  produced  by  a  thoroughgoing  synthesis  of 
reproduction,  then  the  synthesis  of  the  imagination  must 
also  be  founded  a  priori  on  a  principle  prior  to  all 
experience,  and  we  must  assume  a  pure  transcendental 
synthesis  of  the  imagination,  [197]  which  lies  at  the  very 
foundation  of  even  the  possibility  of  any  experience  (as  that 
which  necessarily  presupposes  the  possibility  of  reproducing 
phenomena).  Now,  it  is  plain  that  if  I  draw  a  line  in 
thought,  or  think  of  the  time  from  to-day  at  noon  to  to 
morrow  at  the  same  hour,  or  even  wish  to  represent  to 
myself  any  definite  number,  first  of  all  I  must  necessarily 
grasp  in  thought  these  manifold  representations  successively. 
But  if  I  lost  out  of  mind,  and  could  not  reproduce  the 
earlier  parts  (the  first  part  of  the  line,  the  prior  portions  of 
the  time,  or  the  successively  represented  unities),  whilst  I 
proceed  to  the  succeeding  ones,  there  never  could  arise  a 


197-198]        DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  161 

complete  representation,  nor  any  of  the  thoughts  just 
named — nay,  not  even  the  first  and  purest  fundamental 
representations  ot  space  and  time. 

The  synthesis  of  apprehension,  then,  is  inseparably  con 
nected  with  that  of  reproduction.  And  as  the  former  is 
the  transcendental  foundation  of  the  possibility  of  any 
cognitions  at  all  (not  only  of  the  empirical,  but  of  the 
pure  a  priori  also),  the  reproductive  synthesis  of  the  ima 
ginative  faculty  is  one  of  the  transcendental  operations  of 
the  mind ;  and,  in  reference  to  these,  we  shall  name  this 
faculty  the  transcendental  imagination.1 

3.  Of  the  Synthesis  of  Recognition  in  the  Concept. — 
Without  the  consciousness  that  what  we  now  think  is 
identical  with  what  we  thought  a  moment  ago,  all  repro 
ductions  in  the  series  of  representations  would  be  useless. 
For  what  we  now  think  would  be  a  new  representation 
at  the  present  moment,  not  at  all  belonging  to  the  act  by 
which  it  should  have  been  gradually  pro- [198]  duced  ;  and 
the  manifold  thereof  would  never  make  up  a  totality, 
because  it  must  want  that  unity  which  consciousness  alone 
can  give  it.  If  in  counting  I  were  to  forget  that  the  units 
which  are  now  pictured  to  my  senses  were  added  by  me 
gradually  to  one  another,  I  should  not  cognise  the  genera 
tion  of  quantity  by  the  successive  addition  of  unit  to  unit, 
nor,  consequently,  should  I  know  number ;  for  this  concept 
consists  essentially  in  the  consciousness  of  the  unity  of  the 
synthesis. 

The  very  word  concept  might  of  itself  lead  us  to  this 
remark.  For  it  is  this  one  (single)  consciousness  which 
unites  the  manifold,  gradually  intuited,  and  then  also  repro 
duced  into  one  representation.  This  consciousness,  too, 

1  I  use  the  word  imagination  throughout  for  the  faculty r,  not  for  its 
object,  M. 


162  APPENDIX  A  [198-199 

may  often  be  weak,  so  that  we  perceive  it  only  in  the 
result  and  not  in  the  act ;  that  is  to  say,  we  do  not  join 
it  immediately  with  the  generating  of  the  representation ; 
but  notwithstanding  these  distinctions,  we  must  always 
have  one  single  consciousness,  even  though  it  does  not 
stand  forth  with  striking  clearness,  and  without  it  con 
cepts  (and  consequently  knowledge  of  objects)  are  quite 
impossible. 

And  here  it  is  necessary  to  make  it  clear  what  we  mean 
by  the  expression  :  object  of  representations.  We  have 
said  above,  that  phenomena  are  nothing  but  sensuous 
representations,  and  these  again  must  be  considered  in  the 
very  same  way,  viz.,  not  to  be  objects  (beyond  the  faculty 
of  representation).  What  do  we  mean,  then,  when  we 
speak  of  an  object  corresponding  to  cognition,  and  yet 
distinct  from  it  ?  It  is  easy  to  see  that  this  object  must 
be  thought  as  something  in  general  =  x,  because  outside 
our  cognition  we  surely  possess  nothing  which  we  could 
place  over  against  it,  as  corresponding  to  it. 

[199]  But  we  find  that  our  thought  of  the  relation  of 
cognition  to  its  object  carries  with  it  some  sort  of  necessity, 
since  the  object  is  considered  to  be  that  which  prevents 
our  cognitions  from  being  determined  at  random  or  capri 
ciously,  but  a  priori  in  some  certain  way,  because,  by  being 
referred  to  an  object,  they  must  also  necessarily,  in  relation 
to  that  object,  agree  among  themselves ;  that  is  to  say, 
they  must  have  that  unity  which  constitutes  the  concept  of 
an  object. 

But — since  we  are  only  concerned  with  the  manifold  of 
our  representations,  and  the  x  which  corresponds  to  them 
(the  object),  as  it  must  be  something  different  from  our 
representations,  can  be  to  us  nothing — it  is  clear  that  the 
unity  which  the  object  necessarily  produces  can  be  nothing 


199-200]         DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  163 

else  than  the  formal  unity  of  consciousness  in  the  synthesis 
of  the  multiplicity  of  representations.  We  say  then  :  '  we 
cognise  the  object,'  when  we  have  produced  in  the  manifold 
of  intuition  synthetical  unity.  But  this  unity  would  be 
impossible,  unless  we  were  able  to  produce  the  intuition 
by  means  of  such  a  function  of  synthesis  according  to  rule 
as  renders  necessary  the  reproduction  of  the  manifold  a 
priori,  and  also  a  concept  in  which  it  is  united.  We  think, 
for  example,  of  a  triangle  as  an  object,  in  that  we  are 
conscious  of  the  combination  of  three  right  lines  according 
to  a  rule  by  which  such  an  intuition  can  at  any  time  be 
brought  before  us.  This  unity  of  the  rule  determines  all 
multiplicity,  and  limits  it  to  conditions  which  make  the 
unity  of  a  perception  possible;  and  the  concept  of  this 
unity  is  the  representation  of  object  =  x,  which  I  think  by 
means  of  the  aforesaid  predicates  of  a  triangle. 

All  cognition  requires  a  concept,  however  incomplete 
or  obscure ;  and  this,  in  its  very  form,  is  something  uni- 
[2oo]versal,  and  which  serves  as  a  rule.  So  the  concept 
of  body  according  to  the  unity  of  the  manifold,  which  is 
thought  by  means  of  it,  serves  as  a  rule  for  our  cognition 
of  external  phenomena.  But  it  can  only  become  a  rule 
of  intuition  by  representing,  along  with  given  phenomena, 
the  necessary  reproduction  of  their  multiplicity,  and  con 
jointly  the  synthetical  unity  in  the  consciousness  thereof. 
So  the  concept  of  body,  when  we  perceive  anything  without 
us,  makes  the  representation  of  extension,  and  with  it  that 
of  solidity,  figure,  etc.,  necessary. 

There  is  always  a  transcendental  condition  at  the 
foundation  of  any  necessity.  Hence,  we  must  be  able 
to  find  a  transcendental  ground  of  the  unity  of  conscious 
ness  in  the  synthesis  of  the  manifold  in  all  our  intuitions, 
and  in  all  our  concepts  of  objects  generally — consequently, 


164  APPENDIX  A  [200-201 

in  all  objects  of  experience.  Without  this  it  would  be  im 
possible  to  think  any  object  as  belonging  to  our  intuitions ; 
for  such  object  is  nothing  else  than,  that  something,  of 
which  the  concept  expresses  such  a  necessity  of  synthesis. 

This  original  and  transcendental  condition  is  no  other 
than  Transcendental  Apperception.  The  consciousness 
of  self,  according  to  the  determination  of  our  states  in 
internal  perception,  is  merely  empirical — always  change 
able  ;  there  can  be  no  fixed  or  permanent  self  in  this 
flux  of  our  internal  phenomena ;  and  this  sort  of  con 
sciousness  is  usually  called  the  internal  sense,  or  empirical 
apperception.  That  which  is  necessarily  represented  as 
numerically  identical,  cannot  be  thought  as  such  by  means 
of  empirical  data.  There  must  be  a  condition,  anticipating 
and  rendering  possible  all  experience.  This  condition 
only  can  render  valid  such  a  transcendental  assumption. 

[201]  Neither  can  cognitions  take  place  in  us,  nor  any 
conjunction  or  unity  among  them,  without  this  unity  of 
consciousness,  which  is  prior  to  all  the  data  of  intuition, 
and  by  reference  to  which  alone  all  representation  of 
objects  is  rendered  possible.  This  pure,  original,  un 
changeable  consciousness,  I  intend  to  call  transcendental 
apperception.  That  it  deserves  this  name  is  plain  from 
the  fact,  that  even  the  purest  objective  unity,  namely, 
that  of  a  priori  concepts  (space  and  time),  is  only  possible 
by  the  reference  of  intuitions  to  such  consciousness.  The 
numerical  unity,  then,  of  this  apperception  is  just  as  much 
the  a  priori  basis  of  all  concepts,  as  the  multiplicity  of 
space  and  time  is  the  basis  of  the  intuitions  of  sensibility. 

But  this  very  transcendental  unity  of  apperception 
forms  a  connexion  according  to  laws  of  all  the  possible 
phenomena  so  far  as  they  can  come  together  in  our  experi 
ence.  For  this  unity  of  consciousness  would  be  impossible 


201-202]         DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  165 

if  the  mind,  in  the  cognition  of  the  manifold,  were  not 
self-conscious  of  the  identity  of  the  function  by  means  of 
which  it  connects  this  manifold  synthetically  in  a  cognition. 
Consequently,  the  original  and  necessary  consciousness  of 
the  identity  of  self  is  at  the  same  time  a  consciousness  of 
just  as  necessary  a  unity  of  the  synthesis  of  all  phenomena 
according  to  concepts;  that  is,  according  to  rules  which 
not  only  make  the  phenomena  necessarily  reproducible, 
but  ipso  facto  also  determine  an  object  for  (their)  intuition, 
and  this  object  is  a  concept  of  something  in  which  they 
are  necessarily  connected.  For  the  mind  could  not  pos 
sibly  think  its  own  identity  in  the  multiplicity  of  repre 
sentations,  and  this  too  a  priori,  if  it  had  not  before  its 
eyes  (so  to  speak)  the  identity  of  its  own  action,  which 
subjects  all  the  [202]  empirical  synthesis  of  apprehension 
to  a  transcendental  unity,  and  is  the  necessary  condition  of 
the  connexion  of  this  apprehension  according  to  rules. 
We  shall  now  be  able  to  determine  more  correctly  our 
notion  of  an  object  All  representations  have,  as  such,  their 
object,  and  may  themselves  also  become  the  objects  of 
other  representations.  Phenomena  are  the  only  objects 
which  can  be  given  us  immediately,  and  that  which  in  the 
phenomenon  refers  immediately  to  the  object  is  called 
intuition.  These  phenomena  are  not  things  per  se,  but 
themselves  only  representations,  which,  again,  have  their 
object,  and  this  we  can  no  longer  intuite ;  it  may  therefore 
be  called  the  non-empirical,  or  transcendental  object  =  x. 

The  pure  concept  of  the  transcendental  object  (which 
is  really  in  all  our  cognitions  of  the  same  sort  =  x)  is  that 
which  can  obtain  for  all  our  empirical  concepts  in  general 
reference  to  an  object — that  is,  objective  reality.  Now 
this  concept  can  contain  no  determinate  intuition,  and 
can  therefore  refer  to  nothing  but  that  unity  which  must 


1 66 


APPENDIX  A 


[202-203 


be  found  in  the  multiplicity  of  a  cognition,  so  far  as  it 
stands  in  relation  to  an  object.  But  this  relation  is 
merely  the  necessary  unity  of  consciousness,  and  also  of 
the  synthesis  of  the  manifold  by  a  general  function  of 
the  mind,  which  connects  the  manifold  into  one  repre 
sentation.  Since  this  unity  must  be  regarded  as  necessary 
a  priori  (otherwise  the  cognition  would  have  no  object), 
the  relation  to  a  transcendental  object — that  is,  the  ob 
jective  reality  of  our  empirical  knowledge — depends  on  the 
transcendental  law,  that  all  phenomena  (so  far  as  objects 
are  to  be  given  us  through  them)  must  submit  to  the  a 
priori  rules  of  their  synthetical  unity,  according  to  which 
their  relation  in  empirical  intuition  is  alone  possible. 

[203]  In  short,  phenomena  must  in  experience  stand 
under  the  conditions  of  the  necessary  unity  of  apperception, 
just  as  they  must  stand  in  mere  intuition  under  the  formal 
conditions  of  space  and  time ;  so  that  only  through  the 
former  does  any  cognition  become  even  possible. 

4.  Preliminary  Explanation  of  the  Possibility  of  the 
Categories  as  a  priori  Cognitions. — There  is  only  one  ex 
perience,  in  which  all  perceptions  are  represented  in 
thoroughgoing  and  regular  connexion ;  just  as  there  is 
only  one  space  and  one  time  in  which  all  forms  of  pheno 
mena,  and  all  relations  of  existence  or  non-existence, 
are  found.  When  we  speak  of  different  experiences,  they 
only  mean  so  many  perceptions,  as  far  as  they  belong  to 
one  and  the  same  universal  experience.  The  thorough 
going  and  synthetical  unity  of  perceptions  is  exactly  what 
constitutes  the  form  of  experience,  and  experience  is 
nothing  but  the  synthetical  unity  of  phenomena  according 
to  concepts.  Unity  of  synthesis  according  to  empirical 
concepts  would  be  quite  contingent ;  and,  were  these  not 
based  on  a  transcendental  ground  of  unity,  it  would  be 


203-204]         DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  167 

possible  for  a  confused  crowd  of  phenomena  to  fill  our 
minds,  without  our  ever  forming  experience  from  them. 
But  then  all  reference  of  cognition  to  objects  must  vanish, 
because  the  connexion  of  experience  according  to  universal 
and  necessary  laws  would  be  wanting ;  we  should  then 
have  thoughtless  intuition,  never  amounting  to  knowledge, 
and  so  for  us  equivalent  to  nothing. 

The  a  priori  conditions  of  any  possible  experience  are, 
at  the  same  time,  the  conditions  of  the  possibility  of  the 
objects  of  experience.1  Now  I  assert  that  the  above- 
mentioned  [204]  Categories  are  nothing  but  the  conditions 
of  thinking  in  possible  experience,  just  as  space  and  time  are 
the  conditions  of  the  intuition  which  is  requisite  for  the 
same.  The  former,  then,  are  likewise  fundamental  concepts 
which  enable  us  to  think  objects  in  general  for  phenomena, 
and  are,  accordingly,  objectively  valid — the  very  point  we 
wished  to  ascertain. 

But  the  possibility,  nay  even  the  necessity,  of  these 
Categories  depends  upon  the  relation  in  which  the  whole 
sensibility,  and  with  it  all  possible  phenomena,  must  stand 
to  primitive  apperception;  in  which  apperception  everything 
must  necessarily  accord  with  the  conditions  of  the  thorough 
going  unity  of  self-consciousness,  which  means  that  every 
thing  must  be  subject  to  universal  functions  of  synthesis — 
synthesis  according  to  concepts.  By  this  means  alone  can 
apperception  prove  its  thoroughgoing  and  necessary  identity. 
For  example,  the  concept  of  cause  is  nothing  but  a  synthesis 
(of  that  which  follows  in  the  series  of  time  with  other 

1  That  is  to  say,  the  [subjective]  conditions  of  our  minds,  whereby 
alone  we  become  capable  of  knowing  objects,  must  also  be  the  only 
possible  [and  therefore  necessary]  conditions  of  objects ;  for  without 
submitting  to  these  conditions,  the  objects  cannot  exist  at  all.  It  is 
idle  to  add  for  us,  since  no  noumenon  can  properly  be  called  an 
object.  M. 


1 68  APPENDIX  A  [204-205 

phenomena)  according  to  concepts,  and  without  such  a 
unity,  which  has  its  rule  a  priori  and  controls  the  pheno 
mena,  thoroughly  universal  and  necessary  unity  of  conscious 
ness  could  not  occur  in  the  multiplicity  of  phenomena  :  in 
which  case  these  phenomena  would  belong  to  no  experience, 
and  therefore  be  without  any  object,  but  only  a  random 
play  of  representations,  less  even  than  a  dream. 

All  attempts,  then,  to  deduce  from  experience  these  [205] 
pure  concepts  of  the  understanding,  and  to  give  them  a 
merely  empirical  origin,  are  perfectly  idle  and  useless. 
I  waive  the  point  that  the  concept,  for  example,  of  cause 
carries  with  it  the  feature  of  necessity,  which  could  not  be 
given  by  any  experience,  for  this  indeed  teaches  us,  that 
something  usually  follows  a  certain  phenomenon,  but  never 
that  it  must  follow  necessarily ;  nor  could  it  teach  us  that 
we  may  conclude  a  priori,  and  quite  universally,  from  the 
cause  as  a  condition,  to  the  effect.  But  this  empirical  rule 
of  association,  which  we  must  of  course  assume  as  uni 
versally  applicable,  when  we  say  that  everything  in  the 
series  of  events  is  so  strictly  obedient  to  law,  that  nothing 
happens  without  being  preceded  by  something  upon  which 
it  always  follows — this  rule  I  say,  as  a  law  of  nature,  upon 
what  does  it  depend  ?  How,  I  ask,  is  this  association  even 
possible?  The  foundation  of  the  possibility  of  this  as 
sociation  of  the  manifold,  as  far  as  it  lies  in  the  object,  is 
called  the  affinity  of  the  manifold.  I  ask,  then,  what 
makes  this  thoroughgoing  affinity  of  phenomena  conceivable 
to  you  (by  which  they  stand  under,  and  must  be  subject  to 
permanent  laws)  ? 

Upon  my  principles  it  is  easily  understood.  All  possible 
phenomena  belong,  as  representations,  to  the  whole  of 
possible  self-consciousness.  But  this  being  a  transcend 
ental  representation,  its  numerical  identity  is  indivisible 


205-206]         DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  169 

and  certain  a  priori,  because  we  cannot  possibly  know 
anything,  except  through  this  primitive  apperception.  Now, 
as  this  identity  must  necessarily  be  introduced  into  the 
synthesis  of  all  the  manifold  of  phenomena,  which  are  ever 
to  become  empirical  cognition,  the  phenomena  must  be 
subject  to  a  priori  conditions,  to  which  their  synthesis  (in 
apprehension)  must  thoroughly  [206]  conform.  The  re 
presentation  of  a  general  condition,  according  to  which  a 
certain  multiplicity  can  be  brought  before  us  (that  is  to  say, 
a  definite  way  of  doing  it),  is  called  Rule  ;  if  it  must  be  so 
brought  before  us,  Law.  Consequently  all  phenomena 
stand  in  thorough  connexion  with  one  another  according 
to  necessary  laws,  and  hence  in  a  transcendental  affinity r,  of 
which  the  empirical  is  merely  the  consequence. 

That  nature  must  conform  to  OUT  subjective  apperception 
— nay,  even  that  its  order  must  depend  on  this  relation — 
probably  sounds  very  absurd  and  strange.  But  if  we  reflect 
that  this  nature  is  nothing  in  itself  but  the  sum -total  of 
phenomena,  consequently  nothing  per  se,  but  merely  a 
number  of  mental  representations,  we  need  not  be  surprised 
that  we  see  it  subject  to  the  radical  faculty  of  all  our 
knowledge;  that  is  to  say,  subject  to  transcendental  ap 
perception,  and  hence  subject  to  that  unity  through  which 
alone  it  can  become  the  object  of  any  possible  experience ; 
or,  in  other  words,  become  nature.  It  is  for  the  very  same 
reason  that  we  can  cognise  this  unity  a  priori,  and  therefore 
necessarily,  which  would  be  impossible  were  it  given  in 
itself,  independent  of  the  highest  sources  of  our  thinking. 
In  this  latter  case,  I  know  not  whence  we  could  draw  the 
synthetical  propositions  of  such  a  universal  unity  of  nature; 
for  then  we  must  borrow  them  from  the  objects  of  nature 
themselves.  As  this  could  only  be  done  empirically, 
nothing  could  be  inferred  but  a  contingent  unity,  which 

II  N 


1 7o  APPENDIX  A  [206-207 

is  very  far  from  being  the  necessary  connexion  which  we 
mean  by  the  word  nature. 

[207]  §  3.  Of  the  Relation  of  the  Understanding  to  Objects  in 
general,  and  of  the  Possibility  of  Cognising  them  a  priori. 

The  detached  observations  made  in  the  previous  section 
we  shall  here  unite  and  present  in  a  connected  form.  There 
are  three  subjective  sources  of  cognition,  upon  which  rest 
the  possibility  of  experience  in  general,  and  the  cognition 
of  objects ;  these  are  Sense,  Imagination,  and  Apperception. 
Each  of  these  can  be  considered  empirically,  that  is,  in  its 
application  to  given  phenomena ;  but  all  of  them  are  also 
[original]  elements  [of  the  mind],  and  a  priori  conditions, 
which  make  even  this  empirical  use  possible.  Sense 
represents  phenomena  empirically  in  perception;  Imagination, 
in  association  (and  reproduction) ;  Apperception,  in  the  em 
pirical  consciousness  of  the  identity  of  these  reproduced 
representations  with  the  (original)  phenomena,  that  is  to 
say,  in  Recognition.  But  at  the  a  priori  basis  of  the  whole 
of  our  perceptions  lie  pure  intuitions  (or  if  we  regard  them 
as  representations — the  form  of  internal  intuitions,  time). 
At  the  basis  of  association  lies  the  pure  synthesis  of  the 
imagination ;  and  at  the  basis  of  empirical  consciousness, 
pure  apperception,  that  is,  the  thoroughgoing  identity 
of  self  in  all  possible  representations.  If  we  wish,  then,  to 
analyse  the  internal  causes  of  this  connexion  of  representa 
tions,  till  we  reach  the  point  where  all  representations  must 
meet  (in  order  to  start  with  unity  of  cognition,  which  is  the 
necessary  condition  of  possible  experience),  we  must  begin 
from  pure  apperception.  All  intuitions  are  for  us  nothing, 
and  do  not  the  least  concern  us,  if  they  cannot  be  taken  up 
into  consciousness,  whether  directly  or  indirectly,  and  only 


207-209]        DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  171 

through  this  means  is  cognition  at  all  possible.  We  are 
a  priori  conscious  of  our  own  complete  [208]  identity  in 
regard  to  all  representations  which  can  ever  belong  to  our 
cognition;  and  this  we  regard  as  the  necessary  condition 
of  the  possibility  of  all  representations.  (For  these  only 
represent  anything  in  me,  by  belonging,  with  all  the  rest,  to 
one  consciousness,  in  which  they  can  at  any  rate  be  con 
nected.)  This  principle  is  established  a  priori^  and  may 
be  called  the  transcendental  principle  of  the  unity  of  all 
multiplicity  in  our  representations  (even  in  intuition). 
Now,  the  unity  of  multiplicity  in  one  subject  is  synthetical. 
Pure  apperception,  then,  gives  us  a  principle  of  the  syn 
thetical  unity  of  multiplicity  in  all  possible  intuition.1 

[209]  But  this  synthetical  unity  presupposes  or  implies 

1  Let  us  pay  particular  ^'attention  to  this  proposition,  which  is  of  the 
greatest  importance.  All  representations  have  a  necessary  reference  to 
a  possible  empirical  consciousness  ;  for  if  they  had  not  this  feature, 
and  were  it  quite  impossible  to  become  conscious  of  them,  this  would 
mean  that  they  do  not  exist.  But  all  empirical  consciousness  has  a 
necessary  reference  to  a  transcendental  consciousness  (preceding  all 
particular  experience),  namely,  the  consciousness  of  self,  as  the  primi 
tive  apperception.  It  is  absolutely  necessary  that  in  my  cognition  all 
[acts  of]  consciousness  should  belong  to  one  consciousness  (of  myself). 
Now  this  is  a  synthetical  unity  of  the  manifold  (of  consciousness)  which 
is  cognised  a  priori,  and  which  gives  just  the  same  basis  for  synthetical 
a  priori  propositions  which  relate  to  pure  thinking,  as  space  and  time 
give  to  such  propositions  as  relate  to  the  form  of  mere  intuition.  The 
synthetical  proposition,  that  the  various  empirical  consciousnesses  must 
be  combined  in  one  single  self-consciousness,  is  absolutely  the  first  and 
synthetical  principle  of  our  thinking  in  general.  But  we  must  never 
forget,  that  the  bare  representation  Ego  is  the  transcendental  conscious 
ness  in  relation  to  all  others  (the  collective  unity  of  which  it  renders 
possible).  This  representation  may  then  be  clear  (empirical  conscious 
ness)  or  obscure — a  fact  which  is  here  of  no  importance  ;  nay,  not  even 
the  fact  whether  it  have  any  actuality  or  not ;  but  the  possibility  of  the 
logical  form  of  all  knowledge  rests  necessarily  on  the  relation  to  this 
apperception  as  a  faculty. 


i;2  APPENDIX  A  [209-210 

a  synthesis ;  and  if  the  former  is  to  be  necessary  a  priori, 
the  latter  must  be  an  a  priori  synthesis.  Consequently, 
the  transcendental  unity  of  apperception  points  to  the  pure 
synthesis  of  imagination,  as  an  a  priori  condition  of  the 
possibility  of  any  combination  of  the  manifold  into  a  single 
cognition.  But  it  is  only  the  productive  synthesis  of  the 
imagination  which  can  take  place  a  priori ;  for  the  repro 
ductive  depends  on  empirical  conditions.  Consequently, 
before  apperception,  the  principle  of  the  necessary  unity  of 
the  pure  (productive)  synthesis  of  the  imagination  is  the 
foundation  of  the  possibility  of  any  knowledge,  especially 
of  experience. 

We  denominate  the  synthesis  of  multiplicity  in  the 
imagination  transcendental,  when,  without  distinguishing 
the  intuitions,  it  aims  at  nothing  but  the  combination  of 
multiplicity  a  priori :  and  the  unity  of  this  synthesis  is 
called  transcendental,  if,  as  referring  to  the  original  unity 
of  apperception,  it  is  represented  as  necessary  a  priori. 
Now,  as  this  latter  lies  at  the  foundation  of  all  cognitions, 
the  transcendental  unity  of  the  synthesis  of  the  imagination 
is  the  pure  form  of  all  possible  cognition,  by  means  of 
which  all  objects  of  possible  experience  must  be  represented 
a  priori. 

The  unity  of  apperception  in  relation  to  the  synthesis  of 
the  imagination  is  the  understanding ;  and  this  very  unity, 
in  relation  to  the  transcendental  synthesis  of  the  [210] 
imagination,  is  the  pure  understanding.  There  are,  then, 
in  the  understanding  pure  cognitions  a  priori  which  contain 
the  necessary  unity  of  the  pure  synthesis  of  the  imagina 
tion,  in  reference  to  all  possible  phenomena.  But  these 
are  the  Categories,  or  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding. 
Consequently,  the  empirical  faculty  of  cognition  which 
belongs  to  our  nature  contains  an  understanding  which 


210-21 1]        DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  173 

relates  to  all  objects  of  the  senses,  but  this  only 
mediately,  through  intuition  and  its  synthesis  by  means  of 
the  imagination,  to  which  understanding  all  phenomena 
must  consequently  be  subject,  as  data  for  a  possible  ex 
perience.  But,  as  this  relation  of  phenomena  to  possibly 
experience  is  also  necessary  (because  without  this  they 
would  afford  us  no  cognition,  and  not  concern  us  at  all) 
it  follows,  that  the  pure  understanding,  by  means  of  the 
Categories,  is  a  formal  and  synthetical  principle  of  all 
experiences,  and  phenomena  have  a  necessary  relation  to 
the  understanding. 

We  shall  now  expound  the  necessary  connexion  of  the 
understanding  with  phenomena  by  means  of  the  Categories, 
by  beginning  from  below — from  the  empirical  extremity. 
The  first  thing  given  us  is  the  phenomenon,  which,  if 
combined  with  consciousness,  is  called  perception.  (With 
out  relation  at  least  to  a  possible  consciousness,  the  pheno 
menon  could  never  be  for  us  an  object  of  cognition,  and 
would  hence  be  to  us  as  nothing ;  having  no  .  objective 
reality,  and  only  existing  as  known,  it  would  be  absolutely 
nothing  at  all.)  But  as  every  phenomenon  contains  a 
certain  multiplicity — that  is  to  say,  as  various  perceptions 
are  found  within  us,  in  themselves  scattered  and  single — a 
connexion  of  them  is  necessary,  and  this  they  cannot  have 
in  mere  sense.  There  is,  then,  within  us  an  active  faculty 
of  the  [211]  synthesis  of  this  multiplicity,  which  we  call 
the  faculty  of  Imagination ;  and  the  action  of  which,  when 
directed  immediately  upon  the  perceptions,  I  call  appre 
hension.1  The  province  of  the  imagination  is  to  unite  the 

1  That  the  faculty  of  imagination  is  a  necessary  ingredient  even  in 
perception,  has  perhaps  not  as  yet  struck  any  psychologist.  This 
arises  partly  from  confining  the  faculty  to  mere  reproductions;  partly 
because  it  was  thought  that  the  senses  not  only  gave  us  impressions, 


174  APPENDIX  A  [211-212 

manifold  of  intuition  into  an  image ;  it  must  first,  then, 
grasp  the  impressions  actively,  viz.  apprehend  them. 

But  it  is  clear  that  even  this  apprehension  of  the 
manifold  by  itself  could  produce  no  image,  nor  connexion 
of  impressions,  if  there  were  not  present  a  subjective  con 
dition  for  summoning  a  perception  from  which  the  mind 
had  made  a  transition  to  the  next,  to  join  this  next,  and  so 
produce  whole  series  of  these  perceptions — in  fact,  if  we 
did  not  possess  a  reproductive  faculty  of  the  imagination, 
which  even  then  is  only  empirical.  But  representations,  if 
they  suggested  one  another  just  as  they  chanced  to  meet 
together  originally,  would  have  no  determinate  connexion, 
but  be  a  mere  confused  crowd,  from  which  could  spring 
no  cognition ;  their  reproduction  must  therefore  have  a 
rule  by  which  a  representation  enters  into  combination 
rather  with  this  than  with  another  representation  in  the 
imagination.  The  subjective  and  empirical  ground  of  re 
production  according  to  rules,  we  call  the  association  of 
representations. 

[212]  But  if  this  unity  of  association  had  not  also  an 
objective  basis,  so  as  to  make  it  impossible  for  phenomena 
to  be  apprehended  by  the  imagination  except  under  the 
condition  of  a  possible  synthetical  unity  of  this  apprehension, 
then  it  would  also  be  quite  contingent  that  phenomena, 
when  combined,  should  be  adapted  to  human  cognitions. 
For  although  we  had  the  faculty  of  associating  perceptions, 
it  would  still  be  quite  undetermined  in  itself,  and  acci 
dental,  whether  they  were  also  themselves  capable  of  such 
association ;  and  supposing  they  were  not,  a  quantity  of 

but  even  combined  them,  and  so  brought  images  of  objects  before  us 
— a  process  which,  nevertheless,  most  certainly  requires  somewhat 
besides  the  mere  receptivity  of  impressions,  namely,  a  function  of  their 
synthesis. 


212-213]         DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  175 

perceptions,  and  even  a  whole  sensibility,  would  be  possible, 
in  which  the  mind  might  meet  with  a  great  deal  of  em 
pirical  consciousness,  but  disconnected,  and  without  belong 
ing  to  one  consciousness  of  myself,  which  is  nevertheless  im 
possible.  For  it  is  only  when  I  attribute  all  my  perceptions 
to  one  consciousness  (of  pure  apperception)  that  I  can 
say  I  am  conscious  of  them.  There  must,  then,  be  an 
objective  ground  prior  to  any  of  the  empirical  laws  of 
imagination,  and  a  priori,  on  which  depends  the  possibility 
— nay,  even  the  necessity — of  a  law  extending  over  all 
phenomena;  which  regards  them  universally  to  be  such 
data  of  the  senses  as  are  in  themselves  associable,  and 
subject  to  the  general  rules  of  a  thoroughgoing  connexion 
when  reproduced.  This  objective  basis  of  all  association 
of  representations  I  call  affinity.  We  cannot  meet  it  else 
where  than  in  the  principle  of  the  unity  of  apperception,  as 
regards  all  cognitions  which  can  belong  to  me.  According 
to  this  principle,  every  phenomenon  without  exception 
must  so  enter  the  mind,  or  be  apprehended,  as  to  agree 
with  the  unity  of  apperception,  which  apperception  would 
itself  be  impossible  without  synthetical  unity  in  its  [213] 
connexion ;  this  latter  is,  accordingly,  also  objectively 
necessary. 

The  objective  unity  of  all  (empirical)  consciousness 
in  one  consciousness  (of  primitive  apperception)  is  then 
the  necessary  condition  even  of  all  possible  perception  ;  and 
the  affinity  of  all  phenomena  (proximate  or  remote)  is  the 
necessary  consequence  of  a  synthesis  in  the  imagination, 
which  is  founded  a  priori  upon  rules. 

The  Imagination  is  then  also  a  faculty  01  a  priori 
synthesis,  for  which  reason  we  give  it  the  name  of  the 
productive  imagination ;  and  since,  as  far  as  it  relates  to 
the  multiplicity  of  phenomena,  it  has  no  further  object 


I76  APPENDIX  A  [213-214 

than  to  produce  the  necessary  unity  in  their  synthesis,  we 
may  call  it  the  transcendental  function  of  the  imagination. 
It  is  then  sufficiently  clear  from  what  precedes,  though  it 
may  sound  rather  strange,  that  only  by  means  of  the 
transcendental  function  of  the  imagination  does  even  the 
affinity  of  phenomena,  and  with  it  their  association,  and 
through  this,  too,  their  reproduction  in  accordance  with 
laws — in  fact,  does  experience — become  possible ;  because 
without  it  no  concepts  of  objects  would  ever  coalesce  into 
one  experience. 

For  the  fixed  and  unchanging  Ego  (of  pure  apperception) 
constitutes  the  correlatum  of  all  our  representations,  so  far 
as  it  is  merely  possible  to  become  conscious  of  them; 
and  all  consciousness  belongs  just  as  much  to  an  all-com 
prehensive  pure  apperception  as  all  sensuous  intuition  (qua 
representation)  belongs  to  a  pure  internal  intuition  — 
namely,  that  of  time.  It  is,  then,  this  apperception  which 
must  be  added  to  the  imagination,  to  render  its  function 
intellectual.  For  in  itself  the  synthesis  of  imagination, 
though  exercised  [214]  a  priori,  is  yet  always  sensuous, 
because  it  only  combines  the  manifold  as  .it  appears  in 
intuition — for  example,  the  figure  of  a  triangle.  But  it  is 
only  through  the  relation  of  the  manifold  to  the  unity  of 
apperception  that  concepts  can  be  formed,  and  this  only 
by  means  of  the  imagination  in  relation  to  the  sensuous 
intuition. 

We  have  then  the  pure  imagination,  as  an  original 
faculty  of  the  human  soul,  lying  at  the  basis  of  all  cogni 
tion  a  priori.  By  means  of  it  we  bring  on  the  one  side 
the  multiplicity  of  intuition,  and  on  the  other  the  condition 
of  the  necessary  unity  of  apperception,  into  mutual  relation.1 

1  From  this  point  I  have  developed  my  explanation  of  the  schematism 
of  the  Categories.  M. 


214-215]         DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  177 

Both  extremities — sensibility  and  understanding — must  be 
necessarily  connected  by  means  of  this  transcendental 
function  of  the  imagination ;  otherwise,  there  might  indeed 
be  appearances,  but  no  objects  of  empirical  cognition,  or 
experience.  Actual  experience,  consisting  of  apprehension, 
association  (of  reproduction),  and  finally,  of  the  recognition 
of  phenomena,  contains  in  this  last  and  highest  (merely 
empirical  element  of  experience)  concepts,  which  render 
possible  the  formal  unity  of  experience,  and  with  it  all 
objective  validity  (truth)  of  empirical  cognition.  These 
fundamental  causes  of  the  recognition  of  multiplicity,  so 
far  as  they  concern  merely  the  form  of  experience  in  general, 
are  the  very  categories  of  which  we  are  speaking.  On 
them  is  founded  not  only  all  formal  unity  of  the  synthesis 
of  the  imagination,  but  through  it  the  unity  even  of  all 
that  belongs  to  its  empirical  use  (in  recognition,  repro 
duction,  association,  apprehension)  down  to  phenomena; 
because  it  is  only  by  means  of  [215]  these  elements  of  our 
knowledge  that  phenomena  can  belong  to  our  conscious 
ness,  and  hence  to  ourselves. 

Thus  the  order  and  regularity  in  phenomena,  which  we 
call  nature,  we  ourselves  introduce,  and  should  never  find  it 
there,  if  we,  or  the  nature  of  our  mind,  had  not  originally 
placed  it  there.  For  this  unity  of  nature  must  be  a  ne 
cessary  unity  of  connexion,  that  is  to  say,  certain  a  priori. 
But  how  could  we  possibly  produce  a  priori  a  synthetical 
unity,  if  subjective  foundations  for  such  unity  a  priori 
were  not  contained  in  the  original  sources  of  knowledge  in 
our  mind,  and  if  these  subjective  conditions  were  not  at 
the  same  time  objectively  valid,  by  being  the  very  basis  of 
the  possibility  of  cognising  any  object  at  all  in  experience  ? 

We  have  already  explained  the  Understanding  in  various 
ways :  by  a  spontaneity  of  cognition  (as  opposed  to  the 


i;8  APPENDIX  A  [215-216 

receptivity  of  sensibility),  or  by  a  faculty  of  thinking,  or  of 
concepts,  or  even  of  judgments — all  of  which  explanations, 
if  properly  understood,  coincide.  We  may  now  characterise 
it  as  the  faculty  of  rules.  This  attribute  is  more  fruitful, 
and  explains  its *  nature  better.  Sensibility  gives  us  forms 
(of  intuition),  but  the  understanding  gives  us  rules.  This 
latter  is  always  occupied  in  hunting  through  phenomena, 
in  order  to  find  any  rule  they  may  present.  Rules,  so  far 
as  they  are  objective  (or  belong  necessarily  to  the  cognition 
of  the  object)  are  called  laws.  Although  we  learn  many 
laws  from  experience,  yet  are  these  only  particular  deter 
minations  of  higher  laws,  among  which  the  highest  (to 
which  the  rest  are  subordinate)  are  derived  from  the  [216] 
Understanding  itself,  and  are  not  borrowed  from  experi 
ence,  but  rather  render  phenomena  subject  to  law,  and  by 
this  very  means  make  experience  itself  possible.  The 
understanding  is,  then,  not  merely  a  faculty  of  forming  for 
itself  rules  by  the  comparison  of  phenomena ;  it  is  itself  a 
code  of  laws  for  nature,  that  is  to  say,  without  the  under 
standing  there  would  be  no  nature  at  all,  or  synthetical 
unity  of  phenomena  according  to  rules ;  for  phenomena 
cannot,  as  such,  find  place  without  us,  but  exist  only  in  our 
sensibility.  But  this  [sensibility],  as  an  object  of  know 
ledge  in  experience,  with  all  that  it  may  contain,  is  only 
possible  in  the  unity  of  apperception.  This  unity  of  apper 
ception  is  the  transcendental  basis  of  the  necessary  regu 
larity  of  all  phenomena  in  experience.  The  same  unity  in 
relation  to  the  multiplicity  of  representations  (that  is  to 
say,  determining  it  from  a  single  representation)  is  the  rule, 
and  the  faculty  of  these  rules  is  the  understanding.  Thus 
all  phenomena,  as  possible  objects  of  experience,  lie  a 

1  The    original    is  derselben,   viz.   their  (the   rules)   nature.      My 
emendation,  desselben,  seems  necessary.     M. 


2i6-2i7l         DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  179 

priori  in  the  understanding,  and  receive  from  it  their 
possibility,  just  as  mere  intuitions  lie  in  the  sensibility, 
and,  as  to  form,  are  only  possible  through  it. 

However  exaggerated  or  absurd,  then,  it  may  seem  to 
assert  that  the  understanding  itself  is  the  source  of  the 
laws  of  nature,  and  of  the  formal  unity  thereof,  such  an 
assertion  is  nevertheless  equally  correct  and  applicable  to 
the  object,  that  is,  to  experience.  Empirical  laws,  indeed, 
as  such,  can  by  no  means  deduce  their  origin  from  the  pure 
understanding,  just  as  the  infinite  variety  of  phenomena 
could  not  be  adequately  conceived  from  the  pure  form  of 
sensuous  intuition.  But  all  empirical  laws  are  only  par 
ticular  determinations  of  the  pure  laws  of  the  understanding, 
under  which,  and  ac- [217]  cording  to  the  type  of  which, 
they  first  become  possible ;  so  that  phenomena  assume  a 
fixed  form,  just  as  all  phenomena,  in  spite  of  the  variety 
of  their  empirical  form,  must  nevertheless  always  accord 
with  the  conditions  of  the  pure  form  of  sensibility. 

The  pure  understanding  is,  then,  in  the  Categories,  the 
law  of  the  synthetical  unity  of  all  phenomena ;  and  hence 
it  first  renders  experience  possible  as  to  form.1  But  this 
was  our  whole  aim  throughout  the  transcendental  deduction 
of  the  Categories,  namely,  this  relation  of  the  understanding 
to  sensibility,  and  through  it  to  all  objects  of  experience ; 
in  fact,  to  render  intelligible  the  objective  validity  of  the 
pure  concepts  of  the  understanding,  and  so  to  establish 
their  origin  and  truth. 

1  This  important  limitation  saves  Kant's  system  from  absolute 
idealism.  He  never  asserts  that  the  matter  of  experience  is  created 
by  the  Ego.  M. 


i8o  APPENDIX  A  [217-218 

SUMMARY  STATEMENT  OF    THE    CORRECTNESS  AND    POS 
SIBILITY   OF   THIS   AND   NO   OTHER    DEDUCTION   OF   THE 

PURE  CONCEPTS  OF  THE  UNDERSTANDING. 

WERE  the  objects  with  which  our  knowledge  is  concerned 
things  in  themselves,  we  could  not  have  any  a  priori 
concepts  of  them.  For  from  whence  could  we  obtain  such 
concepts  ?  Suppose  we  took  them  from  the  object  (without 
pausing  to  investigate  how  this  could  become  known  to  us 
at  all),  then  our  concepts  would  be  [218]  merely  empirical, 
and  not  a  priori.  Suppose  we  took  them  from  ourselves, 
then  that  which  is  merely  within  us  could  not  determine 
the  nature  of  an  object  distinct  from  our  representations ; 
that  is  to  say,  it  could  not  form  a  reason  why  there  should 
exist  a  thing  to  which  our  thoughts  should  correspond, 
rather  than  that  such  representations  should  be  totally  void. 
On  the  contrary,  if  we  are  altogether  concerned  only  with 
phenomena,  it  is  not  only  possible,  but  even  necessary, 
that  certain  a  priori  concepts  should  antecede  the  empirical 
cognition  of  objects.  For,  as  phenomena,  they  produce  an 
object  which  exists  only  in  us,  because  a  mere  modification 
of  our  sensibility  cannot  exist  without  us.  Now  this  very 
representation — that  all  these  phenomena,  and  objects  with 
which  we  can  employ  ourselves,  are  all  in  me,  that  is,  are 
determinations  of  my  identical  self — this  representation, 
I  say,  expresses  their  complete  unity  in  one  and  the  same 
apperception  to  be  necessary.  But  in  this  unity  of  possible 
consciousness  consists  also  the  form  of  all  cognition  of 
objects  (by  which  multiplicity  is  thought  as  belonging  to 
one  object).  So  that  the  way  in  which  the  manifold  of 
sensuous  representations  (intuition)  belongs  to  one  con 
sciousness,  precedes  all  cognition  of  the  object,  as  being  its 
intellectual  form,  and  even  produces  a  formal  cognition  of 


218-219]        DEDUCTION  OF  THE  CATEGORIES  181 

all  objects  a  priori,  so  far  as  they  are  thought  (Categories). 
Their  synthesis  through  the  pure  imagination,  and  the 
unity  of  all  representations  in  relation  to  primitive  appercep 
tion,  precede  all  empirical  cognition.  Consequently,  all 
pure  concepts  of  the  understanding  are  only  for  this  reason 
possible — nay,  even  in  relation  to  experience,  necessary — 
that  our  knowledge  is  concerned  with  no- [219]  thing  but 
phenomena,  the  possibility  of  which  lies  within  ourselves, 
and  the  conjunction  and  unity  of  which  (in  the  representa 
tion  of  an  object)  are  to  be  found  only  in  ourselves ;  so 
that  these  must  precede  all  experience,  and  make  it  even 
possible  as  to  form.  It  is  then  on  this,  the  only  possible 
basis,  that  our  deduction  of  the  Categories  has  been  con 
structed. 


[220]    APPENDIX    B 

DISTINCTION    BETWEEN    NOUMENA  AND 
PHENOMENA 

(a.)  AFTER  the  words  'under  such  conceptions,'  p.  181 
(Meiklejohn's  translation),  the  following  paragraph  occurs  in 
the  First  Edition  : — 

'  Above,  in  the  exposition  of  the  table  of  the  Categories, 
we  saved  ourselves  the  trouble  of  denning  each  of  them, 
because  our  object,  which  concerned  merely  their  synthetical 
use,  did  not  require  it,  and  we  should  not,  by  needless 
undertakings,  incur  responsibilities  which  we  can  avoid. 
This  was  not  an  evasion,  but  an  unavoidable  rule  of  pru 
dence,  not  to  venture  forthwith  into  definitions,  and  to 
attempt  or  pretend  to  completeness  in  the  determination 
of  -a  concept,  when  one  or  two  of  its  attributes  suffice, 
without  our  requiring  a  complete  enumeration  of  all  that 
make  up  the  whole  concept.  But  it  now  appears  that  the 
ground  of  this  precaution  lies  deeper,  namely,  that  we 
could  not  define  them  if  we  wished  to  do  so.1  For,  if  we 

1  I  mean  here  real  definition,  which  does  not  merely  substitute  for 
the  name  of  a  thing  other  more  intelligible  terms,  but  that  which 
contains  in  it  a  distinct  attribute  by  which  the  object  (definitum]  can 
always  be  certainly  recognised,  and  which  renders  the  defined  concept 
useful  in  application.  The  real  explanation  would  then  be  that  which 


220-222]  NOUMENA  AND  PHENOMENA  183 

get  rid  of  all  the  [221]  conditions  of  sensibility  which  mark 
them  as  concepts  that  can  possibly  be  used  empirically, 
and  take  them  for  concepts  of  things  in  general  (that  is,  of 
transcendental  application),  then  nothing  further  can  be 
done  with  them  than  to  regard  the  logical  function  in 
judgments  as  the  condition  of  the  possibility  of  things 
themselves ;  without  there  being  the  least  evidence  how 
they  could  then  have  their  application  and  object,  or  how 
they  could  then  have  any  meaning  and  objective  validity  in 
the  pure  understanding,  apart  from  sensibility.' 

(/?.)  Instead  of  the  note  on  p.  182,  the  First  Edition 
has  the  following  : — 

'  It  appears  somewhat  strange,  and  even  absurd,  that 
there  should  be  a  concept  which  is  to  have  a  signification 
but  is  not  capable  of  any  explanation.  But  the  Categories 
are  here  so  peculiarly  circumstanced  that,  though  they  can 
only  have  a  definite  signification  and  reference  to  any 
object  by  means  of  the  universal  sensuous  condition,  yet  this 
condition  has  been  left  out  of  the  pure  Category,  which  in 
consequence  can  contain  nothing  but  the  logical  function 
of  bringing  the  manifold  under  a  concept.  But  from  this 
function — that  is,  from  the  form  of  the  concept  alone — it 
cannot  at  all  be  known  what  object  falls  under  it,  because 
abstraction  has  been  made  from  that  very  sensuous  con 
dition,  owing  to  which  alone  objects  in  general  can  come 
under  the  [222]  Category.  Hence  the  Categories  require, 
beyond  the  mere  concept  of  the  understanding,  determina 
tions  of  their  application  to  sensibility  in  general  (schemata}, 
and  without  this  are  not  concepts  by  which  any  object  can 
be  cognised  and  distinguished  from  another  :  they  are  rather 

makes  distinct  not  only  a  concept,  but  at  the  same  time  its  objective 
reality.  Mathematical  explanations,  which  present  the  object  in  accord 
ance  with  the  concept  in  intuition,  are  of  this  latter  sort. 


1 84  APPENDIX  B  [222-223 

so  many  ways  of  thinking  an  object  for  possible  intuitions, 
and  giving  it  its  signification  (under  conditions  yet  to  be 
supplied),  according  to  some  function  of  the  understanding, 
that  is,  of  defining  it :  but  these  Categories  cannot  them 
selves  be  defined.  The  logical  functions  of  judgments  in 
general — unity  and  plurality,  affirmation  and  negation, 
subject  and  predicate — cannot  be  defined  without  arguing 
in  a  circle,  because  such  definition  cannot  but  be  a 
judgment,  and  must  therefore  contain  these  functions. 
But  the  pure  Categories  are  representations  of  things  in 
general,  so  far  as  the  diversity  of  their  intuition  must  be 
thought  through  one  .or  other  of  these  logical  functions : 
Quantity  is  the  determination  which  can  only  be  thought 
through  a  judgment  having  quantity  (judidum  commune} ; 
Reality,  that  which  can  only  be  thought  through  an  affirma 
tive  judgment ;  Substance,  that  which,  in  reference  to 
intuition,  must  be  the  ultimate  subject  of  all  other  deter 
minations.  But  what  sort  of  things  they  are,  in  reference 
to  which  we  must  employ  this  function  rather  than  that, 
still  remains  quite  undetermined.  So  that  the  Categories, 
without  the  condition  of  sensuous  intuition  (provided  they 
contain  the  synthesis),  have  no  definite  relation  to  any 
object,  hence  cannot  define  any  such  object,  and  have  not, 
consequently,  in  themselves  the  validity  of  objective  con 
cepts.' 

The  passage  commencing  'but  there  lurks'  (p.  184), 
and  ending  '  negative  sense '  (p.  186),  was  re-written  [223]  in 
the  Second  Edition.  Its  original  form  was  as  follows : — 

'Appearances,  so  far  as  they  are  thought  as  objects, 
according  to  the  unity  of  the  Categories,  are  called  pheno 
mena.  But  if  I  assume  things,  which  are  merely  the  objects 
of  the  understanding,  and  which  can,  at  the  same  time,  be 
presented  to  an  intuition,  though  not  a  sensuous  one  (as 


223-224]  NOUMENA  AND  PHENOMENA  185 

coram  intuitu  intellectual}),  then  such  things  would  be  called 
noumena  (intelligibilia). 

Now  it  might  be  imagined  that  the  concept  of  phenomena, 
limited  as  it  was  in  the  transcendental  Aesthetic,  suggests 
of  itself  the  objective  reality  of  the  noumena,  and  justifies 
the  division  of  all  objects  into  phenomena  and  noumena ; 
and  so  of  the  world  into  one  of  sense  and  reason  (nmndus 
sensibilis  et  intelligibilis).  And  indeed  the  difference  would 
not  seem  to  be  the  logical  form  of  the  distinct  or  indistinct 
knowledge  of  one  and  the  same  object,  but  would  start  from 
the  difference  of  the  way  in  which  they  are  given  to  our 
cognition,  and  according  to  which  they  must  differ  from 
one  another  in  themselves  generically.  For  if  the  senses 
represent  something  only  as  it  appears,  this  something  must 
surely  be  also  a  thing  in  itself,  and  the  object  of  a  non- 
sensuous  intuition,  that  is,  of  the  understanding.  In  such 
case  there  must  be  a  cognition  possible,  in  which  no  sensi 
bility  can  be  found,  and  which  alone  possesses  absolutely 
objective  reality,  viz.  by  which  objects  are  represented  to 
us  as  they  are ;  whereas,  on  the  contrary,  in  the  empirical 
use  of  our  understanding,  things  are  only  cognised  as  they 
appear.  Accordingly,  beyond  the  empirical  use  of  the 
Categories  (which  is  restricted  to  sensuous  conditions), 
there  would  be  still  [224]  a  pure  and  objectively  valid  one; 
and  we  could  not  assert,  as  we  have  claimed  to  do  so  far, 
that  our  pure  understanding-cognitions  are  nothing  but 
principles  of  the  exposition  of  appearance,  and  do  not 
reach  any  further  a  priori  than  the  formal  possibility  of 
experience ;  for  here  quite  another  field  would  lie  open  to 
us,  as  it  were  a  world  thought  in  the  spirit  (perhaps  even 
intuited),  upon  which  we  could  employ  our  understanding 
just  as  much,  and  far  more  nobly. 

Now  all  our  representations  are,  in  fact,  referred  to  some 

II  O 


1 86  APPENDIX  B  [224-223 

object  by  the  understanding,  as  phenomena  are  nothing 
but  representation ;  and  so  the  understanding  refers  them 
to  something,  as  the  object  of  sensuous  intuition ;  but  this 
something  is  so  far  merely  the  transcendental  object.  But 
this  signifies  a  something  =  x,  of  which  we  know  nothing  ; 
nor  can  we  (according  to  the  present  constitution  of  our 
understanding)  know  anything  of  it,  as  being  that  which 
can  serve  only  as  a  correlate  of  the  unity  of  apperception  to 
obtain  the  unity  of  diversity  in  sensuous  intuition,  by  means 
of  which  the  understanding  unites  this  diversity  in  the 
concept  of  an  object.  This  transcendental  object  cannot 
be  at  all  separated  from  the  sensuous  data,  because  then 
nothing  remains  by  which  it  would  be  thought.1  [223] 
[This  x  then]  is  no  object  of  cognition  in  itself,  but  only 
the  representation  of  phenomena  under  the  concept  of  an 
object  in  general,  which  is  determinable  by  the  diversity  of 
the  phenomena. 

For  this  reason,  the  Categories  do  not  represent  any 
definite  object  given  to  the  understanding  alone,  but  only 
serve  to  determine  the  transcendental  object  (the  concept 
of  something  in  general),  by  what  is  given  in  sensibility,  so 
as  by  it  to  cognise  empirically  phenomena  under  concepts 
of  objects. 

But  as  to  the  reason  why  we  (not  satisfied  with  the 
substratum  of  sensibility)  have  added  noumena  to  the 

1  This  clause  Kuno  Fischer  omits  in  his  account  of  the  matter 
(Cotnm.  p.  131),  though  it  explains  and  limits  Kant's  meaning,  in  the 
passages  quoted  by  him  (pp.  190  and  195)  in  italics.  Because  nothing 
is  left  for  us,  when  we  subtract  all  the  subjective  conditions  of  the 
object,  it  does  not  follow  that  nothing  at  all  remains.  Hence,  through 
out  this  passage  Kant  never  asserts  the  thing  per  se  not  to  exist.  His 
private  opinion  seems  to  have  been  that  it  did  exist ;  and  this  is  often 
implied  in  his  language,  though  not  dogmatically  stated,  being  just  as 
indemonstrable  as  the  opposed  doctrine.  M. 


223-224]  NOUMENA  AND  PHENOMENA  187 

phenomena,  which  the  pure  understanding  alone  can  think, 
it  rests  simply  upon  this  :  Sensibility  and  its  sphere  (viz. 
that  of  phenomena)  are  restricted  by  the  understanding  to 
this,  that  they  shall  concern  not  things  per  se,  but  only  the 
way  in  which  things  appear  to  us  according  to  our  sub 
jective  constitution.  This  was  the  result  of  the  whole 
transcendental  Aesthetic ;  and  it  also  follows  naturally  from 
the  very  concept  of  a  phenomenon  in  general,  that  some 
thing  must  correspond  to  it  which  in  itself  is  not  pheno 
menon,  because  phenomenon  can  be  nothing  in  itself 
beyond  our  faculty  of  representation;  so  that,  unless  we 
are  involved  in  a  perpetual  circle,  the  very  word  phenomenon 
indicates  a  reference  to  something,  the  immediate  representa 
tion  of  which  indeed  is  sensuous,  but  which  in  itself,  even 
without  this  constitution  of  our  sensibility  (upon  which  the 
form  of  our  intuition  is  based),  must  still  be  some-  [224] 
thing,  that  is,  an  object  independent  of  our  sensibility. 

Now  from  this  originates  the  concept  of  a  noumenon, 
which  is,  however,  not  at  all  positive,  or  a  definite  cognition 
of  any  particular  thing,  but  only  signifies  the  thought  of 
something  in  general,  by  abstracting  from  all  the  form  of 
sensuous  intuition.  But  in  order  that  a  noumenon  should 
signify  a  true  object,  to  be  distinguished  from  all  phenomena, 
it  is  not  enough  for  me  to  rid  my  thoughts  of  all  the  con 
ditions  of  sensuous  intuition  ;  I  must,  over  and  above  this, 
have  some  reason  for  assuming  another  sort  of  intuition 
than  sensuous,  to  which  such  an  object  could  be  given : 
otherwise  my  thought,  though  not  self-contradictory,  is  still 
void.  We  have,  indeed,  not  been  able  to  demonstrate  in 
the  text  that  sensuous  intuition  was  the  only  possible  one 
whatever,  but  merely  that  it  was  so  for  us ;  but  neither 
were  we  able  to  prove  that  any  other  kind  of  intuition  was 
possible  ;  and  although  our  thought  can  abstract  from  all 


!88  APPENDIX  B  [224-225 

sensibility,  the  question  still  remains  to  be  settled — whether 
it  is  then  anything  but  the  mere  form  of  a  concept ;  and 
whether,  when  such  abstraction  is  made,  any  object  at  all  is 
left.1 

The  object  to  which  I  refer  the  phenomenon  in  general 
is  the  transcendental  object,  that  is,  the  totally  unde 
termined  thought  of  something  in  general.  This  [225] 
cannot  be  called  the  noumenon  ;  for  I  do  not  know  what  it 
is  in  itself,  and  have  no  concept  of  it  at  all,  except  as  the 
object  of  sensuous  intuition  in  general,  which  is,  accordingly, 
of  the  same  description  for  all  phenomena.  I  cannot  think 
it  by  means  of  any  Category ;  for  such  is  valid  only  of 
empirical  intuition,  in  order  to  subject  it  to  the  concept  of 
an  object  in  general.  A  pure  use  of  the  Categories  is 
indeed  possible,  or  not  contradictory,  but  has  no  objective 
validity,  because  it  concerns  no  intuition  on  which  it 
confers  the  unity  of  an  object;  for  the  Category  is  only 
a  pure  function  of  thought,  by  which  no  object  can  be 
given  me,  but  by  which  I  only  think  what  is  given  in 
intuition. 

1  Here  is  the  question  of  absolute  idealism  explicitly  raised  ;  and  the 
following  paragraph  proceeds,  not  to  solve  it  dogmatically,  but  merely 
to  show  that  no  possible  data  can  be  found  for  settling  the  question. 
There  being  such  total  absence  of  proofs,  may  not  the  necessary 
suggestion  of  noumena  by  phenomena  be  allowed  some  weight  ?  M. 


[226]  APPENDIX   C 

THE   FIRST   PARALOGISM   OF   SUBSTANTIALITY  1 

THAT  of  which  the  representation  is  the  absolute  subject 
of  our  judgments,  and  which  consequently  cannot  be  used 
to  determine  anything  else  [as  predicate],  is  substance. 

I,  as  a  thinking  being,  am  the  absolute  subject  of  all  my 
possible  judgments,  and  this  representation  of  myself  cannot 
be  used  as  the  predicate  of  anything  else. 

Therefore  I,  as  a  thinking  being  (soul),  am  substance. 

KRITIK  OF  THE  FIRST  PARALOGISM  OF  PURE 
PSYCHOLOGY 

We  have  shown  in  the  analytical  part  of  the  transcend 
ental  Logic  that  pure  Categories  (and  among  them  that  of 
Substance)  have  in  themselves  no  objective  meaning  at  all, 
except  when  based  on  an  intuition,  to  the  di-  [227]  versity 
of  which  they  can  be  applied,  as  functions  of  the  synthetical 
unity.  Without  this,  they  are  merely  functions  of  judgment, 
without  content.  Of  anything  in  general,  I  may  say  it  is 
substance,  so  far  as  I  distinguish  it  from  the  mere  predicates 
and  determinations  of  things.  Now  in  all  our  thinking,  the 

1  The  following  discussion  stood  in  the  First  Edition  after  the  words 
'  predicaments  of  pure  psychology  '  (p.  241). 


190  APPENDIX  C  [227-228 

Ego  is  the  subject,  in  which  thoughts  inhere  merely  as 
determinations,  and  this  Ego  cannot  be  used  to  determine 
anything  else.  Consequently,  every  one  must  necessarily 
consider  himself  as  the  substance,  and  his  thoughts  as  the 
accidents,  of  his  existence,  and  determinations  of  his 
condition.  But  what  use  can  I  make  of  this  notion  of  a 
substance  ?  That  I,  as  a  thinking  being,  exist  permanently ; 
that  I  cannot  naturally  either  originate  or  pass  away — this 
I  cannot  at  all  infer  from  it,  and  yet  it  is  the  only  use  of 
the  concept  of  the  substantiality  of  my  thinking  subject, 
with  which  I  could  otherwise  very  well  dispense. 

We  are  so  far  from  being  able  to  conclude  these 
properties  from  the  mere  pure  Category  of  substance,  that 
we  are  obliged  to  start  from  the  permanence  of  an  object 
derived  from  experience,  if  we  wish  to  bring  such  an  object 
under  the  empirically  applicable  concept  of  substance.  Now, 
in  the  proposition  we  are  discussing,  we  have  not  taken  any 
experience  for  our  basis,  but  have  drawn  our  conclusion 
simply  from  the  concept  of  the  relation  which  all  thought 
has  to  the  Ego,  in  which  it  inheres,  as  its  common  subject. 
Neither  could  we,  supposing  we  desired  to  do  it,  establish 
such  a  permanence  by  any  safe  observation.  For  the  Ego 
is  present  indeed  in  all  thoughts;  but  there  is  not  the 
least  intuition  connected  with  this  representation,  to  dis 
tinguish  it  from  other  objects  of  intuition.  We  may  then 
indeed  perceive  that  this  representation  is  ever  recurring  in 
every  act  of  [228]  thought,  but  not  that  it  is  the  fixed  and 
permanent  intuition  in  which  thoughts  (being  transient) 
alternate.1 

1  He  here  approaches  as  closely  as  possible  to  the  refutation  of 
idealism  in  his  Second  Edition.  According  to  the  First  Edition  also, 
all  change  must  take  place  in  a  permanent,  [and  (Second  Edition)  a 
permanent  homogeneous  with  it].  This  permanent  is  not  the  Ego 


228-229]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY     191 

It  follows,  that  the  first  syllogism  of  transcendental 
psychology  only  palms  off  upon  us  a  pretended  discovery, 
by  setting  up  the  constant  logical  subject  of  thinking  as 
the  cognition  of  the  real  subject  of  inherence.  Of  this 
latter  we  neither  have,  nor  can  have,  the  least  knowledge, 
because  consciousness  is  the  only  thing  which  makes  all 
our  representations  thoughts,  and  wherein  all  our  perceptions 
must  be  found,  as  their  transcendental  subject ;  and  beyond 
this  logical  meaning  of  the  Ego,  we  have  no  knowledge  of 
the  subject  in  itself,  which  lies  as  substratum  at  the  basis  of 
this  [representation  of  self],  as  well  as  of  all  other  thoughts. 
The  proposition,  then,  the  soul  is  a  substance,  may  be 
allowed  to  stand,  provided  we  keep  in  mind  that  this  notion 
leads  us  no  further,  and  cannot  teach  us  any  of  the 
usual  conclusions  of  sophistical  psychology ;  for  example, 
its  permanence  through  all  changes,  and  even  after  death. 
It  denotes  then  a  substance  only  in  Idea,  but  not  in 
reality. 

THE  SECOND  PARALOGISM,  OF  SIMPLICITY 

A  thing,  of  which  the  action  cannot  be  regarded  as  the 
concurrence  of  the  action  of  several  things,  is  simple. 
[229]  Now  the  soul,  or  thinking  Ego,  is  such  a  thing. 
Therefore,  etc. 

KRITIK  OF  THE  SECOND  PARALOGISM  OF  TRANSCEND 
ENTAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

This  is  the  Achilles  of  all  the  dialectical  syllogisms  of 
pure  psychology  ;  not  merely  a  play  of  sophistry  ingeniously 
contrived  by  the  dogmatical  philosopher,  to  produce  some 

[  (First  Edition,  above  ; )  ]  therefore,  it  must  be  an  external  permanent 
(Second  Edition).     M. 


192 


APPENDIX  C  [229-230 


show  of  argument  for  his  assertions,  but  a  conclusion  which 
seems  to  withstand  the  most  acute  investigation,  and  the 
most  circumspect  consideration.  Here  it  is  : — 

Every  composite  substance  is  an  aggregate  of  many ;  and 
the  action  of  any  composite,  or  that  which  inheres  in  it  as 
such,  is  the  aggregate  of  many  actions  or  accidents,  divided 
among  a  number  of  substances.  Now,  an  effect  which 
arises  from  the  concurrence  of  several  acting  substances 
is  possible  when  this  effect  is  merely  external  (as,  for 
instance,  the  motion  of  a  body  is  the  joint  motion  of  all  its 
parts).  But  the  case  is  different  with  thoughts,  which  are 
accidents  belonging  internally  to  a  thinking  being.  For 
supposing  that  this  composite  did  think,  each  part  of  it 
would  contain  part  of  the  thought ;  but  all  of  them  only 
when  combined,  the  whole  thought.  Now  this  is  con 
tradictory.  For  since  the  representations  which  are  con 
tained  under  the  different  parts  (suppose  the  individual 
words  of  a  verse)  are  never  [by  themselves]  a  whole  thought 
(a  verse),  so  thought  cannot  be  inherent  in  a  composite  as 
such.  Thought,  therefore,  is  only  [230]  possible  in  a 
substance  which  is  not  an  aggregate  of  many  substances, 
but  absolutely  simple.1 

The  so-called  nervus  probandi  of  this  argument  lies  in 
the  proposition  :  that  many  representations  must  be  con 
tained  in  the  absolute  unity  of  the  thinking  subject,  to 
make  up  one  thought.  But  this  proposition  no  one  can 
prove  from  concepts.  For  how  could  he  even  commence 
his  argument  ?  The  proposition  :  a  thought  can  only  be 
the  effect  of  the  absolute  unity  of  the  thinking  being — 
cannot  be  treated  analytically.  For  the  unity  of  a  thought 

1  It  is  very  easy  to  give  this  proof  in  the  usual  scholastic  form.  But 
it  is  sufficient  for  my  purpose  to  present  its  ground  of  proof  though 
merely  in  a  popular  form. 


230-231]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    193 

which  consists  of  many  representations  is  collective,  and,  as 
far  as  pure  concepts  go,  might  just  as  well  refer  to  the 
collective  unity  of  the  co-operating  substances  (like  the 
motion  of  the  body  being  the  composite  motion  of  its 
parts),  as  to  the  absolute  unity  of  the  subject.  Proceeding 
then  according  to  the  rule  of  identity,  we  cannot  see  the 
necessity  of  presupposing  a  simple  substance  to  account 
for  a  composite  thought.  But  that  this  proposition  should 
be  recognised  synthetically  and  perfectly  a  priori  from  pure 
concepts,  no  one  will  venture  to  assert,  who  understands 
the  basis  of  the  possibility  of  synthetical  a  priori  judgments, 
as  already  set  forth. 

Now  it  is  equally  impossible  to  deduce  from  experience 
this  necessary  unity  of  the  subject,  as  the  condition  of  the 
possibility  of  each  single  thought.  For  experience  could 
give  no  necessity,  and  besides  the  concept  of  absolute  unity 
is  far  beyond  its  sphere.  Whence  then  do  we  [231]  get 
this  proposition,  on  which  the  whole  psychological  syllogism 
rests  ? 

It  is  plain  that,  if  we  wish  to  represent  a  thinking  being, 
we  must  put  ourselves  in  its  place,  and  so  supply  our  own 
subject  to  the  object  which  we  wish  to  obtain  (which  is  not 
the  case  in  any  other  sort  of  investigation),  and  that  we 
only  demand  the  absolute  unity  of  the  subject,  because 
otherwise  we  could  not  say :  I  think  (the  manifold  of  the 
representation).  For,  although  the  sum  of  the  thought 
might  be  divided  and  distributed  among  many  subjects,  yet 
the  subjective  Ego  cannot  be  divided  or  distributed,  and 
this  we  certainly  presuppose  in  all  thinking. 

Here,  then,  as  in  the  previous  paralogism,  the  formal 
proposition  of  apperception,  /  think,  is  also  the  whole  basis 
upon  which  rational  psychology  ventures  to  extend  her 
cognitions — a  proposition  which  is  not  experience,  but 


I94 


APPENDIX  C  [231-232 


merely  the  form  of  apperception,  belonging  to,  and  pre 
ceding,  every  experience.  But  with  reference  to  possible 
cognition,  this  must  be  regarded  merely  as  a  subjective 
condition,  which  we  have  no  right  to  exalt  to  a  condition  of 
the  possibility  of  objects,  that  is,  to  a  concept  of  a  thinking 
being  in  general,  [merely]  because  we  cannot  represent 
such  a  being  to  ourselves,  without  putting  ourselves  with 
the  formula  of  our  consciousness  in  the  place  of  every 
other  intelligent  being. 

The  simplicity  of  myself  (as  a  soul)  is  not  actually  in 
ferred  from  the  proposition,  I  think ;  for  it  already  exists 
in  every  thought.  The  proposition,  /  am  simple,  must  be 
regarded  as  an  immediate  expression  of  apperception,  just 
as  the  supposed  Cartesian  conclusion,  cogito  ergo  sum,  is 
really  tautological,  as  cogito  (  =  sum  cogitans)  expressly  asserts 
existence.  /  am  [a]  simple  [being]  [232]  means  nothing 
but  this — that  the  representation  /  does  not  contain  the 
least  multiplicity,  and  that  it  is  an  absolute  (although 
merely  logical)  unity. 

Consequently,  this  celebrated  psychological  demonstra 
tion  is  merely  based  upon  the  indivisible  unity  of  a  repre 
sentation  which  only  directs  the  verb  \cogitare\  to  refer  to 
a  person.  But  it  is  plain  that  the  subject  of  inherence  is 
only  indicated  as  transcendental  by  the  Ego  attached  to 
the  thought,  without  noting  in  the  least  any  of  its  properties, 
and  without  knowing  or  cognising  anything  at  all  about  it. 
It  means  something  in  general  (a  transcendental  subject), 
the  representation  of  which  must  indeed  be  simple,  for  the 
obvious  reason  that  nothing  at  all  is  determined  in  it,  since 
we-  cannot  represent  a  thing  more  simply  than  by  the 
notion  of  a  mere  something.  But  the  fact  of  the  simplicity 
of  the  representation  of  a  subject  is  not,  for  that  reason,  a 
cognition  of  the  simplicity  of  the  subject  itself;  total 


232-233]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    195 

abstraction  being  made  from  its  properties,  when  it  is 
merely  indicated  by  the  perfectly  contentless  expression 
Ego  (which  I  can  apply  to  every  thinking  subject). 

So  much  is  certain,  that  I  represent  to  myself  by  Ego 
always  an  absolute,  though  only  a  logical,  unity  of  the 
subject  (Simplicity),  but  do  not  cognise  through  it  the 
actual  simplicity  of  my  subject.  As  the  proposition,  I  am. 
substance,  means  nothing  but  the  pure  Category,  of  which 
I  can  make  no  concrete  use  (empirically),  so  I  may  also 
be  allowed  to  say,  I  am  a  simple  substance,  that  is,  one 
whose  representation  never  contains  a  synthesis  of  multi 
plicity  ;  but  this  concept,  or  even  this  proposition,  does  not 
give  us  the  least  information  with  regard  to  myself  as  an 
object  of  experience,  because  the  concept  of  substance 
itself  is  only  used  as  a  function  of  [233]  synthesis,  without 
being  based  on  intuition,  that  is,  without  any  object;  so 
that  it  only  applies  to  the  condition  of  our  knowledge, 
not  to  any  object  which  we  could  name.  Let  us  make 
an  experiment  with  regard  to  the  supposed  use  of  this 
proposition. 

Every  one  must  confess  that  the  assertion  of  the  simple 
nature  of  the  soul  is  merely  of  value  so  far  as  I  am  able 
by  it  to  separate  this  subject  from  all  matter,  and  con 
sequently  exempt  it  from  decay,  to  which  matter  is  always 
liable.  It  is  for  this  use  that  the  above  proposition  is 
specially  intended,  and  it  is  therefore  often  thus  expressed : 
The  soul  is  not  corporeal.  Now  if  I  can  show  that,  even 
conceding  to  this  cardinal  proposition  of  rational  psychology 
all  objective  validity  (that  all  which  thinks  is  simple  sub 
stance),  in  the  pure  meaning  of  a  mere  judgment  of  the 
Reason  (from  pure  Categories) — even  conceding  this,  I  say 
— not  the  least  use  can  be  made  of  it  with  reference  to  its 
dissimilarity  or  relation  to  matter,  then  I  may  fairly  claim 


>96  APPENDIX  C  [233-234 

to  have  relegated  this  pretended  philosophical  truth  into 
the  region  of  pure  Ideas,  which  are  wanting  in  reality  when 
objectively  used. 

We  have  proved  irrefragably  in  our  transcendental 
Aesthetic  that  bodies  are  mere  phenomena  of  our  external 
sense,  and  not  things  in  themselves.  In  accordance  with 
this  we  may  say  justly,  that  our  thinking  subject  is  not 
corporeal,  viz.  that  as  it  is  represented  to  us  as  an  object 
of  the  internal  sense,  it  cannot,  so  far  as  it  thinks,  be  an 
object  of  the  external  senses,  or  a  phenomenon  in  space. 
This  is  equivalent  to  saying  :  Thinking  beings,  as  such,  can 
never  be  represented  to  us  among  external  intuitions ;  or, 
we  cannot  intuite  their  thoughts,  consciousness,  desires, 
etc.  externally;  for  all  these  must  [234]  come  before  the 
internal  sense.  This  argument  indeed  appears  to  be  also 
the  natural  and  popular  one,  which  seems  to  have  satisfied 
even  the  most  ordinary  understandings,  so  that  from  very 
early  times  they  began  to  consider  souls  as  totally  distinct 
from  bodies. 

Now  extension,  incompressibility,  connexion,  and  motion 
— in  short,  all  that  our  external  senses  only  can  give  us — 
are  not,  and  indeed  do  not  contain,  thought,  feeling,  desire, 
or  resolve,  which  are  not  at  all  objects  of  external  intuition. 
Nevertheless,  that  something  which  lies  at  the  basis  of 
external  phenomena — which  so  affects  our  sense  as  to  give 
it  the  representations  of  space,  matter,  form,  etc. — that 
something,  I  say,  considered  as  a  noumenon  (or  perhaps 
better  as  a  transcendental  object),  might  also  at  the  same 
time  be  the  subject  of  thoughts,  although  we  may  not  be 
able  to  obtain  any  intuition  of  mental  states  (but  only  of 
space  and  its  determinations),  through  the  means  by  which 
our  external  sense  is  affected.  But  this  something  is  not 
extended,  impenetrable,  or  composite,  because  all  these 


234-235]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    197 

predicates  only  concern  sensibility  and  its  intuition,  so  far 
as  we  are  affected  by  that  sort  of  objects  (otherwise  un- 
unknown  to  us).  Yet  these  expressions  by  no  means 
declare  to  us  what  sort  of  an  object  it  is,  but  only  this, 
that  the  predicates  of  external  phenomena  cannot  be  ap 
plied  to  it,  considered  as  an  object  in  itself,  and  without 
reference  to  external  senses.  But  the  predicates  of  the 
internal  sense — representation  and  thinking — do  not  con 
tradict  it.  Consequently,  even  admitting  the  simplicity 
of  its  nature,  the  human  soul  is  not  at  all  proved  to 
be  distinct  from  matter,  as  regards  their  respective  sub 
strata^  when  considered  (as  it  should  be)  merely  as  a 
phenomenon. 

If  matter  were  a  thing  per  se,  it  would,  as  a  composite 
[235]  being,  be  altogether  different  from  the  soul,  as  a 
simple  being.  But  it  is  only  an  external  phenomenon,  of 
which  the  substratum  is  not  cognised  by  any  producible 
predicates.  I  might,  then,  be  quite  justified  in  assuming 
of  this  substratum  that  it  was  in  itself  simple,  although  in 
the  way  which  it  affects  our  senses  it  produces  in  us  the 
intuition  of  extension,  and,  along  with  it,  of  composition. 
It  might  follow  that  this  substance,  to  which  extension  is 
added  by  reference  to  our  external  sense,  is  accompanied 
by  thoughts  in  itself,  which  through  its  own  peculiar  in 
ternal  sense  can  be  represented  with  consciousness.  In 
this  way  the  very  same  thing  which  in  one  relation  is  called 
corporeal,  is  at  the  same  time  in  another  called  a  thinking 
being,  whose  thoughts  indeed  we  cannot  intuite,  but  only 
their  evidences,  in  phenomena.  We  should  thus  get  rid 
of  the  expression,  that  souls  only  (as  being  a  peculiar  sort 
of  substances)  think  ;  we  should  rather  use  the  ordinary 
phrase,  that  men  think ;  that  is  to  say,  that  the  very  same 
thing  which  is  extended  as  an  external  phenomenon,  is 


i98  APPENDIX  C  [235-236 

internally  (in  itself)  a  subject  not  composite,  but  simple 
and  thinking. 

But,  without  admitting  such  hypotheses,  we  may  observe 
in  general,  that  if  I  mean  by  soul  a  ^thinking  being  per  se,  the 
very  question  is  improper,  if  we  mean  to  ask  whether  it  is 
of  the  same  kind,  or  not,  as  matter  (which  is  not  a  thing 
per  se,  but  only  a  sort  of  representation  in  us) ;  for  it  is 
self-evident  that  a  thing  per  se  must  be  of  a  different  nature 
from  the  determinations  which  merely  constitute  its  states.1 

But,  if  we  compare  the  thinking  Ego,  not  with  matter, 
but  with  the  intelligible  something  at  the  basis  of  the  [236] 
external  phenomena,  which  we  call  matter,  as  we  know 
nothing  of  this  latter,  we  cannot  assert  that  the  soul  differs 
from  it  in  any  way  internally.2 

Accordingly,  simple  consciousness  is  not  a  cognition 
of  the  simple  nature  of  our  subject,  so  far  as  it  is  to 
be  distinguished  as  such  from  matter  as  a  composite 
existence. 

But  if  this  concept  of  simplicity  is  useless  in  the  only 
case  where  it  could  be  of  service  (that  is,  to  determine  the 
peculiar  and  distinguishing  feature  of  our  subject,  when  I 
compare  myself  with  the  objects  of  external  experience), 
we  may  fairly  despair  of  ever  knowing  that  /,  the  soul  (a 
name  for  the  transcendental  object  of  the  internal  sense), 
am  simple.  This  expression  has  no  application  extending 

1  Cf.  Fischer's  Commentary,  p.  56,  note. 

2  The  tone  of  the  whole  preceding  passage  corroborates  the  view 
I  have  taken  of  the  intelligible  and  empirical  characters,   and  shows 
that  Kant  (at  least  in  his  opinions]  seems  to  have  ascribed  far  more 
certainty  and  actuality  to  the  noumenon  of  internal,  than  to  that  of  ex 
ternal  phenomena.     At  the  same  time,  he  never  asserts  this  (because 
indemonstrable) ;  it  is  also  remarkable  that,  though  he  contemplates 
the  possibility  of  noumenal  monism,  he  never  suggests  the  possibility 
of  noumenal  nihilism.     M. 


236-237]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    199 

to  actual  objects,  and  cannot  possibly,  therefore,  enlarge  our 
knowledge. 

If  these  remarks  are  true,  the  whole  of  rational  psycho 
logy  falls  to  the  ground  with  its  principal  support ;  and  we 
can  as  little  here  as  elsewhere  hope  to  extend  our  informa 
tion  by  pure  concepts  (still  less  by  consciousness,  the  mere 
subjective  form  of  all  our  concepts).  More  especially,  the 
fundamental  notion  of  a  simple  nature  is  such  that  it 
cannot  be  found  in  any  experience  at  all ;  so  that  there 
is  no  way  of  reaching  it  as  an  objectively  valid  concept. 

[237]  THE  THIRD  PARALOGISM,  OF  PERSONALITY 

That  which  is  conscious  of  its  own  numerical  identity  at 
different  times  is,  so  far,  a  Person. 

Now,  the  soul  has  this  consciousness. 
Therefore,  it  is  a  Person. 

KRITIK  OF  THE  THIRD  PARALOGISM  OF  TRANSCEND 
ENTAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

If  I  desire  to  cognise  the  numerical  identity  of  an  exter 
nal  object  by  experience,  I  pay  attention  to  the  permanent 
[part]  of  the  phenomenon,  to  which,  as  subject,  all  the  rest 
refers  as  determination,  and  remark  the  identity  of  the 
former  in  time,  while  the  latter  changes.  But  I  am  an 
object  of  the  internal  sense,  and  all  time  is  merely  the 
form  of  the  internal  sense.  Consequently,  I  refer  my 
successive  modifications,  one  and  all,  to  the  numerically 
identical  self  in  all  time,  that  is,  in  the  form  of  the  internal 
intuition  of  myself.  Upon  this  ground  the  personality  of 
the  soul  should  be  regarded,  not  as  an  inference,  but  as  a 
perfectly  identical  assertion  of  self-consciousness  in  time ; 
and  this,  too,  is  the  reason  why  it  is  valid  a  priori.  For  it 
says  nothing  but  this :  In  all  the  time  in  which  I  am  con- 


200  APPENDIX  C  [237-239 

scious  of  myself,  I  am  conscious  of  this  time,  belonging  to 
the  unity  of  myself;  and  it  is  indifferent  whether  I  say,  The 
whole  of  time  is  in  me,  who  am  an  individual  unity ;  or,  I 
am,  with  my  numerical  identity,  present  in  all  this  time. 

Personal  identity,  then,  must  be  always  found  in  my  [238] 
own  consciousness.  But,  if  I  consider  myself  from  the  point  of 
view  of  another  person  (as  an  object  of  his  external  intuition), 
this  observer  external  to  me  first  of  all  considers  me  in  time  , 
for  [though]  in  [my  internal]  apperception  time  is  properly 
only  represented  in  mel  He  will,  consequently,  not  con 
clude  the  objective  permanence  of  myself  from  the  Ego, 
which  accompanies  all  representations  at  all  times  in  my  con 
sciousness,  and  indeed  with  perfect  identity,  even  though  he 
concedes  its  presence.  For,  as  the  time  in  which  the 
observer  places  me  is  not  that  which  is  met  with  in  my  sensi 
bility,  but  in  his,  the  identity  which  is  necessarily  bound 
up  with  my  consciousness  is  not  bound  up  with  his,  that 
is,  with  an  external  intuition  of  my  subject. 

[239]  The  identity,  then,  of  the  consciousness  of  myself  at 
different  times  is  only  a  formal  condition  of  my  thoughts 

1  Kant's  argument  appears  to  be  as  follows  :  When  I  regard  my  own 
internal  phenomena,  I  find  them  to  be  all  subject  to  the  condition  of 
time  ;  but  this  time,  again  (and  the  phenomena  in  it),  I  perceive  always 
as  in  me,  as  a  form  of  my  internal  sensibility ;  hence,  in  [internal] 
apperception  self  is  the  highest  condition,  to  which  time  is  subject. 
For  this  reason  the  identity  of  self  has  been  regarded  as  the  necessary 
condition  of  my  existence  in  time.  This  is  true  subjectively  (in  apper 
ception),  but  not  so  objectively,  or  absolutely  ;  for,  suppose  another  man 
perceives  me,  he  perceives  me  through  his  external  sense,  and  I  am 
[also]  to  him  in  time.  But,  though  he  readily  admits  and  believes  in 
my  consciousness  being  accompanied  with  a  full  consciousness  of  identity, 
this  identity  is  not  to  him  the  condition  of  the  time  in  which  he  places 
me.  He  places  me  in  time,  instead  of  placing  time  in  me.  And  the 
feeling  of  identity  which  he  allows  in  me  is  to  him  no  proof  that  myself 
is  objectively  permanent ;  for  it  is  not  necessarily  implied  by  the  time  in 
which  he  places  me.  M. 


239-240]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    201 

and  their  connexion,  and  does  not  demonstrate  the 
numerical  identity  of  my  subject,  in  which,  notwithstanding 
the  logical  identity  of  the  Ego,  such  a  change  might  have 
taken  place  as  to  preclude  its  [numerical]  identity.  We 
might  nevertheless  always  attribute  to  it  that  Ego,  which  never 
varies  in  name,  and  which  in  every  different  state,  even  were 
the  subject  changed,  could  yet  always  preserve  the  thought 
of  the  previous  subject,  and  hand  it  over  to  the  succeeding.1 
Although  the  proposition  of  some  ancient  schools — that 
everything  is  in  a  flux,  and  nothing  permanent — cannot 
stand  if  we  assume  substances,  it  is  not  refuted  by  the  unity 
of  self-consciousness ;  for  we  ourselves  cannot  decide  from 
our  own  consciousness  whether  we,  as  souls,  are  permanent  or 
not,  because  we  only  consider  that  to  belong  to  our  identical 
selves,  of  which  we  [240]  are  conscious  ;  and  so,  of  course,  we 
judge  necessarily  that  we  are  the  very  same  in  the  whole 
time  of  which  we  are  conscious.  But  from  the  point  of 
view  of  a  stranger  we  cannot  hold  this  to  be  a  valid 
inference ;  because,  as  we  meet  in  the  soul  no  permanent 
phenomenon  except  the  representation  self,  which  accom 
panies  and  connects  all  the  rest,  we  can  never  ascertain 
whether  this  Ego  (a  mere  thought)  is  not  subject  to  the  same 
flux  as  the  remaining  thoughts  which  are  connected  by  it. 

I  An  elastic  ball  which  strikes  full  upon  a  similar  one  imparts  to  it 
all  its  motion,   or  all  its  state  (if  we  merely  regard  places  in  space). 
Now,  let  us  assume  substances  after  the  analogy  of  such  bodies,  where 
each  [reading  je\  imparts  representations  to  the  next,  along  with  a  con 
sciousness  of  them.     We  might  thus  conceive  a  whole  series  of  them, 
the  first  of  which  imparted  its  state,  and  the  consciousness  thereof,  to 
the  second  ;  this  again  its  own  state,  along  with  that  of  the  first,  to 
the  third  ;  this  again  its  own  and  the  states  of  all  the  previous  ones,  etc. 
In  such  a  case  the  last  substance  would  be  conscious  of  all  the  states 
of  the  previously  changed  substances  as  its  own,   since  those  states 
were   transferred  to  it  along  with  the  consciousness  of  them  ;  never 
theless,  it  would  not  have  been  the  very  same  person  in  all  these  states, 

II  P 


202 


APPENDIX  C  [240-241 


But  it  is  remarkable  that  the  personality,  and  the  perma 
nence  which  it  presupposes — that  is,  the  substantiality  of 
the  soul — must  now  be  proved  first ;  for,  could  we  pre 
suppose  it,  there  would  follow,  not  indeed  the  permanence 
of  consciousness,  but  the  possibility  of  a  lasting  conscious 
ness  in  a  permanent  subject;  and  this  is  sufficient  for 
personality,  which  need  not  itself  cease,  even  though  its 
action  be  interrupted  for  a  time.  But  this  permanence  is 
not  given  us  at  all  before  the  numerical  identity  of  our 
selves,  which  we  infer  from  the  identity  of  apperception,  but 
is  rather  inferred  from  that  identity  (and  after  this,  to  make 
the  argument  valid,  should  follow  the  concept  of  substance, 
which  is  the  only  one  of  them  that  is  of  empirical  use). 
Now,  as  this  identity  of  person  by  no  means  follows  from 
the  identity  of  the  Ego  in  all  the  time  in  which  I  cognise 
myself — so  we  already  found  that  the  substantiality  of  the 
soul  could  not  be  based  upon  it. 

Nevertheless,  the  concept  of  personality  (as  well  as  that 
of  substance  and  simplicity)  may  remain,  so  far  as  it  is 
transcendental,  and  means  a  unity  of  the  subject  other 
wise  unknown  to  us,  but  in  whose  states  there  is  thorough 
going  connexion  through  apperception.  And  [241]  so  far 
indeed  this  concept  is  both  necessary  and  sufficient  for  all 
practical  uses ;  but  we  can  never  depend  upon  it  to  extend 
our  self-cognition  through  pure^Reason  (which  mirrors  to  us 
a  permanence  of  the  subject),  from  the  mere  concept  of  the 
identical  self,  as  this  concept  always  revolves  about  it  itself, 
and  does  not  assist  in  solving  a  single  question  which  aims 
at  synthetical  cognition.  What  sort  of  thing  per  se  (tran 
scendental  object)  matter  may  be  is  wholly  unknown  to 
us ;  nevertheless,  its  permanence  as  phenomenon  may  be 
observed  when  it  is  represented  as  something  external. 
But  when  I  wish  to  observe  the  mere  Ego  in  the  alteration 


241-242]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    203 

of  all  representations — as  I  have  no  other  correlation  for 
my  comparisons  except  the  same  identical  self  with  the 
universal  conditions  of  my  consciousness — I  can  only  give 
tautological  answers  to  all  questions  by  supplying  my  concept, 
and  its  unity,  to  those  properties  which  I  possess  as  an 
object,  and  so  by  assuming  what  was  under  investigation. 

THE  FOURTH  PARALOGISM,  OF  IDEALITY  (OF  EXTERNAL 
RELATIONS)  * 

Whatsoever  can  only  be  inferred  to  exist,  as  the  cause 
of  given  perceptions,  has  only  a  doubtful  [problematical] 
existence. 

Now,  all  external  phenomena  are  of  such  a  kind  that 
their  present  existence  cannot  be  perceived  immediately,  but 
we  infer  them  to  exist  as  the  cause  of  given  perceptions. 

[242]  Consequently,  the  existence  of  all  the  objects  of 
the  external  senses  is  doubtful.  This  uncertainty  I  call  the 
ideality  of  external  phenomena;  and  the  doctrine  which 
holds  this  ideality  is  Idealism,  in  contrast  to  which  the  asser 
tion  of  a  possible  certainty  of  objects  of  the  external  senses 
is  called  Dualism. 

KRITIK  OF  THE  FOURTH  PARALOGISM  OF  TRANSCEND 
ENTAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

We  shall  first  analyse  the  premises.  We  may  justly  assert 
that  only  what  is  within  us  can  be  immediately  perceived, 
and  that  my  own  existence  alone  is  the  object  of  a  bare 
perception.  Consequently,  the  existence  of  an  actual  object 

1  This  paralogism  does  not  appear  in  the  Second  Edition  probably 
because  the  '  Refutation '  had  already  settled  the  question  as  to  the 
relative  dignity  and  priority  of  our  internal  and  external  experi 
ence.  M. 


204 


APPENDIX  C  [242-243 


without  me  (if  this  word  be  used  in  an  intellectual  sense)  is 
never  given  immediately  in  perception,  but  can  only  be  added 
in  thought  to  the  perception  (which  is  a  modification  of  our 
internal  sense)  as  its  external  cause,  and  so  inferred  from  it. 
Consequently,  Descartes  justly  restricted  all  perception  in  the 
strictest  sense  to  the  proposition,  I  (as  a  thinking  being) 
exist  \  for  it  is  clear  that,  as  the  external  is  not  in  me,  it  can 
not  possibly  be  found  in  my  apperception,  or  in  any  percep 
tion,  which  is  properly  only  a  determination  of  apperception. 

I  cannot,  then,  properly  perceive  external  things,  but 
only  infer  their  existence  from  my  internal  perception  by 
regarding  it  as  an  effect,  of  which  something  external  is  the 
proximate  cause.  But  the  inference  from  a  given  effect  to 
a  determinate  cause  is  always  [243]  precarious,  because  the 
effect  may  have  been  produced  by  more  than  one  cause. 

Consequently,  with  regard  to  the  relation  of  perception 
to  its  cause,  it  must  ever  remain  doubtful  whether  such 
cause  be  internal  or  external — whether  all  so-called  external 
perceptions  are  not  a  mere  play  of  our  internal  sense,  or 
whether  they  indeed  refer  to  actual  external  objects  as  their 
causes.  At  all  events,  the  existence  of  the  latter  is  only  an 
inference,  and  runs  the  risk  of  all  inferences ;  while,  on  the 
contrary,  the  object  of  the  internal  sense  (I  myself,  with 
all  my  representations)  is  perceived  immediately,  and  its 
existence  can  be  in  no  doubt.1 

By  idealist^  then,  we  must  not  understand  the  man  who 
denies  the  existence  of  external  objects,  but  only  one  who 
will  not  concede  that  it  is  known  by  immediate  perception, 

1  This  is  the  very  question  discussed  in  the  much  abused  Refutation 
of  Idealism,  in  the  Second  Edition.  The  definition  of  idealism 
which  immediately  follows  above,  shows  how  strictly  Kant  confined 
both  this  and  the  corresponding  refutation  in  the  later  Editions  to 
Descartes,  and  did  not  consider  Berkeley,  as  Fischer  and  other  Germans 
allege.  M. 


243-244!  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    205 

and  who  concludes,  accordingly,  that  we  can  never  be 
absolutely  certain  of  their  actuality  by  any  possible  experience. 

Now,  before  I  propound  our  paralogism  in  its  delusive 
form,  I  must  observe  that  we  must  necessarily  distinguish 
two  sorts  of  idealism — transcendental  and  empirical.  By 
the  transcendental  idealism  of  all  phenomena,  I  mean  the 
doctrine  according  to  which  we  regard  them  all  as  mere  re 
presentations,  not  as  things  perse,  and  according  to  which  space 
and  time  are  merely  [244]  sensuous  forms  of  our  intuition, 
not  determinations  given  per  se,  or  conditions  of  objects  as 
things  per  se.  Opposed  to  this  doctrine  is  transcendental 
Realism,  which  regards  space  and  tjme  as  something  given 
per  se  (independent  of  our  sensibility).  The  transcendental 
Realist,  then,  represents  to  himself  external  phenomena  (if 
we  allow  their  actuality)  as  things  per  se,  which  exist  in 
dependent  of  us  and  our  sensibility,  and  should  therefore 
also  be  without  us  according  to  pure  concepts.  This 
transcendental  Realist  is  the  proper  man  to  turn  empirical 
idealist ;  and,  after  he  has  falsely  assumed  of  objects  of  our 
senses,  that  if  they  are  to  be  external,  they  must  possess 
existence  in  themselves  apart  from  the  senses,  he  then  finds 
all  the  representations  of  our  senses  insufficient  to  guarantee 
the  actuality  of  these  representations.1 

The  transcendental  idealist,  on  the  contrary,  can  be  an 
empirical  Realist,  or,  as  he  is  called,  a  Dualist ;  that  is,  he 
can  concede  the  existence  of  matter  without  going  beyond 
mere  self-consciousness,  or  assuming  anything  beyond  the 
certainty  of  the  representations  in  me,  or  the  cogito  ergo  sum. 
For  since  he  considers  this  matter,  and  even  its  internal 
possibility,2  to  be  nothing  but  phenomenon,  which  apart 
from  our  sensibility  is  nothing  at  all,  he  only  considers  it  as 
a  kind  of  representations  (intuition)  which  are  called  ex- 
1  Cf.  Fischer's  Commentary^  p.  189.  2  Cf.  vol.  i.  p.  268,  note. 


206  APPENDIX  C  [244-245 

ternal,  not  as  if  they  referred  to  objects  external  in  themselves?- 
but  because  [245]  they  refer  perceptions  to  space,  in  which  all 
things  are  reciprocally  external,  while  space  itself  is  within  us. 
We  have  declared  ourselves  in  favour  of  this  tran 
scendental  idealism  throughout.  Accepting  our  doctrine,  all 
difficulty  of  admitting  the  existence  of  matter  on  the 
testimony  of  our  mere  consciousness  vanishes,  as  well  as  of 
declaring  it  so  proved,  just  as  the  existence  of  myself  as  a 
thinking  being  is  so  proved.  For  I  am  surely  conscious  of 
my  representations ;  these  then,  and  I  who  have  them,  exist. 
But  external  objects  (bodies)  are  mere  phenomena,  and 
nothing  at  all  but  a  species  of  my  representations,  the 
objects  of  which  only  exist  through  these  representations, 
and  apart  from  them  are  nothing.  External  things,  there 
fore,  exist  just  as  much  as  I  myself  do,  and  both  upon  the 
immediate  evidence  of  my  self- consciousness ;  with  this 
difference,  that  the  representation  of  myself  as  a  thinking 
subject  is  referred  only  to  the  internal  sense,  but  the 
representations  which  denote  extended  existences  are 
referred  also  to  the  external  sense.  With  regard  to  the 
actuality  of  external  objects,  I  have  just  as  little  need  of 
inference  as  with  regard  to  the  actuality  of  the  object  of  my 
internal  sense  (my  thoughts) ;  for  they  are  both  nothing 
but  representations,  the  immediate  perception  (conscious 
ness)  of  which  is  likewise  a  sufficient  proof  of  their 
actuality.2 

1  Kant  here  asserts  the  doctrine  of  transcendental  idealism  to  be  this  : 
that  external  phenomena  do  not  refer  to  objects  in  themselves  external 
to  us.     From  this  Kuno  Fischer  infers  (loc.  cit.}  that  Kant  denied  any 
noumenon  to  exist  as  the  (hidden)  basis  of  external  phenomena.     This 
inference  is  unwarranted  ;  for,  in  Kantian  language,  neither  could  the 
noumenon  be  called  an  object,  nor  external  (in  this  sense) ;  so  that  the 
present  argument  does  not  touch  that  question.     Cf.  below,  p.  208.     M. 

2  This  is  the  precise  doctrine  of  the  refutation  of  idealism  in  the 


246-247]   PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    207 

[246]  The  transcendental  idealist  is  then  an  empirical  real 
ist,  and  allows  matter,  as  phenomenon,  an  actuality  which 
need  not  be  inferred,  but  is  immediately  perceived. 
Transcendental  Realism,  on  the  other  hand,  necessarily 
becomes  perplexed,  and  is  forced  to  make  way  for  empirical 
idealism,  because  it  regards  the  objects  of  external  senses  as 
something  distinct  from  the  senses  themselves,  and  mere 
phenomena  as  independent  beings  existing  without  us. 
However  perfectly  we  may  be  conscious  of  our  representa 
tion  of  these  things,  this  is  far  from  proving  that,  if  the 
representation  exists,  its  corresponding  object  must  also 
exist ;  while  on  our  system,  these  external  things  (or  matter, 
in  all  its  forms  and  changes)  are  nothing  but  mere 
phenomena,  or  representations  in  us,  of  whose  actuality  we 
are  immediately  conscious. 

As  all  the  psychologists  who  subscribe  to  empirical 
idealism  are,  as  far  as  I  know,  also  transcendental  realists, 
they  have  been  perfectly  consistent  in  attaching  great 
weight  to  empirical  idealism,  as  one  of  those  problems  which 
human  reason  can  hardly  solve.  For,  most  assuredly, 
if  we  regard  external  phenomena  as  representations  which 
are  produced  in  us  by  their  object — a  thing  per  se  existing 
without  us — then  how  can  its  existence  be  known,  except 
by  inferring  the  cause  [247]  from  the  effect,  in  which  case  it 
must  always  remain  doubtful  whether  this  latter  be  within  or 
without  us.  Now  it  may  indeed  be  conceded  that  some 
thing  is  possibly  the  cause  of  our  external  intuitions,  which 
is  without  us  in  the  transcendental  sense ;  but  this  is  not 

Second  Edition  (Kritik,  p.  167).  The  concluding  limitation  is  also 
there  distinctly  implied  in  the  statement  (p.  166)  that  the  Aesthetic  has 
removed  all  possibility  of  making  space  a  property  of  things  per  se.  '  For 
in  such  case  both  it  and  they  become  perfectly  impossible  and  absurd.' 
Yet  the  argument  which  follows  has  been  interpreted  by  all  Kant's 
critics  as  implying  this  absurdity  !  M. 


2o8  APPENDIX  C  [247-248 

the  object  which  we  understand  by  the  representations  of 
matter  and  corporeal  things ; l  for  these  are  mere  phe 
nomena — mere  species  of  representation — which  are  in  all 
cases  only  within  us ;  and  their  actuality  rests  upon 
immediate  consciousness,  just  as  the  consciousness  of  my 
thoughts  does.  The  transcendental  object,  as  well  of 
internal  as  of  external  intuition,  is  to  us  equally  unknown. 
Not  this  however,  but  the  empirical  object,  is  in  question, 
which  is  called  external  if  it  is  in  space — internal,  if  it  is 
represented  in  time-relations  only ;  but  space  and  time  are 
both  only  to  be  found  within  us. 

But,  as  the  expression  without  us  is  unavoidably 
ambiguous  (meaning  either  that  which  exists  as  a  thing  per 
set  distinct  from  us,  or  merely  that  which  belongs  to  external 
phenomena),  in  order  to  secure  to  this  concept  the  latter 
meaning — being  that  in  which  the  psychological  question 
about  the  reality  of  our  external  intuition  [248]  arises — we 
shall  distinguish  empirically  external  objects  from  those 
possibly  so  called  in  a  transcendental  sense,  by  denominating 
them  simply  things  which  can  be  perceived  in  space. 

Space  and  Time  are  indeed  representations  a  priori 
present  to  us  as  forms  of  our  sensuous  intuition,  before  any 
actual  object  has  determined  us  by  sensation  to  represent 
it  under  these  sensuous  relations.  But  this  material  or  real 
something,  which  is  to  be  intuited  in  space,  necessarily 

1  The  theory  which  Kant  is  here  opposing  asserts  that  there  are 
external  objects,  corresponding  to,  and  resembling  in  some  way,  our 
perceptions.  He  does  not  here  desire  to  refute  his  own  doctrine,  that 
there  are  possibly  noumena  at  the  basis  of  phenomena,  but  to  prove  that 
these  noumena  cannot  be  objects  in  space.  If  this  be  the  meaning  of 
his  argument  (which  is  somewhat  obscurely  expressed),  Kuno  Fischer  is 
just  as  much  mistaken  in  asserting  that  Kant  here  denies  any  special 
noumena  for  external  phenomena,  as  he  is  in  interpreting  the 
'  Refutation  of  idealism  '  to  be  the  assertion  of  noumena  in  space.  M. 


248-249]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    209 

presupposes  perception,1  and  cannot  be  in  any  way  imagined 
or  produced  independently  of  this  perception,  which 
announces  the  actuality  of  something  in  space.  It  is  then 
sensation  which  indicates  actuality  in  space  and  time,  as 
soon  as  this  sensation  has  been  referred  to  either  species  of 
sensuous  intuition.  Sensation,  when  applied  to  an  object 
in  general,  without  determining  it,  is  called  perception. 
This  sensation  being  given,  by  means  of  its  manifoldness 
we  can  imagine  various  objects  which,  beyond  imagination, 
have  no  empirical  place  in  space  or  time.  Whatever 
examples  then  of  sensations  we  take,  whether  pleasure  or 
pain,  or  external  ones  like  colour  and  heat,  this  remains 
quite  certain,  that  perception  is  that  through  which  the  ma 
terial  must  be  given,  in  order  to  supply  objects  to  sensuous 
intuition.  This  perception  then  (to  keep  to  external 
intuitions  at  present),  represents  something  actual  in  space. 
For  in  the  first  place,  perception  is  the  repre-  [249]  sentation 
actuality,  as  space  is  of  the  mere  possibility,  of  simultaneous 
existence.  Secondly,  this  actuality  is  represented  for  the 
external  sense,  that  is,  in  space.  Thirdly,  space  itself  is 
nothing  but  mere  representation.  Nothing  then  can  be 
considered  as  actual  in  space,  except  that  which  is  repre 
sented  in  it;2  and,  vice  versa,  what  is  given  in  space  (or 

1  Here  is  an  assertion  expressly  contradicting  Kuno  Fischer's  doctrine 
that  the  external  thing  is  (in  itself)  nothing  but  our  sensation.     It  pre 
supposes,  as  a  necessary  condition  of  being  perceived,  our  faculty  of 
perception,  but  cannot  be  asserted  identical  with  it.      The  sequel  is 
still  more  explicit.     M.  _ 

2  This  paradoxical,  but  true,  proposition  should  be  carefully  noted — 
viz.,  nothing  is  in  space  except  what  is  represented  in  it.     For  space 
itself  is  nothing  but  representations  ;  consequently,   whatsoever  is  in 
space  must  be  contained  in  the  representation,  and  there  is  nothing  at 
all   in  space  except  so  far  as  it  is  actually  represented  in  it.     The 
assertion,  no  doubt,  sounds  strange — that  a  thing  can  only  exist  in  its 
own  representation  ;  but  the  absurdity  is  here  obviated  since  we  are 


210 


APPENDIX  C  [249-250 


represented  through  perception)  is  also  actual  in  it;  for, 
were  it  not  actual  in  it — that  is,  were  it  not  given  im 
mediately  by  empirical  intuition — it  could  not  be  invented, 
because  the  real  element  in  intuitions  cannot  at  all  be 
obtained  by  a  priori  thinking. 

All  external  perception,  then,  proves  immediately  that 
there  is  something  actual  in  space,  or  rather  it  is  itself  this 
very  actuality,  and  so  far  empirical  realism  is  beyond 
question ;  that  is  to  say,  there  corresponds  to  external  in 
tuitions  something  actual  in  space.  It  is  true  that  space 
itself,  with  all  its  phenomena,  only  exists  within  me ;  but 
nevertheless  in  this  space  reality,  or  the  material  of  all 
objects  of  external  intuition,  is  given  actually  and  inde 
pendently  of  all  invention.  It  is  also  impossible  that  in 
this  space  anything  without  us  (in  the  transcendental  sense) 
should  be  given,  because  space  itself,  apart  from  our 
sensibility,  is  nothing.  The  most  extreme  idealist  cannot, 
then,  call  upon  us  to  prove  that  the  [250]  object  without 
us  (in  the  strict  sense)  corresponds  to  our  perception.  For 
if  such  a  thing  did  exist,  it  could  not  be  represented  or  in 
tuited  as  without  us,  since  this  would  presuppose  space ; 
and  actuality  in  space,  as  of  a  mere  representation,  is 
nothing  but  the  perception  itself.  That  which  is  real  in 
external  phenomena  is  only  actual  in  perception,  nor  can  it 
be  actual  in  any  other  sense. 

From  perception  we  can  produce  objects,  either  by  the 
play  of  fancy,  or  through  experience.  And  so,  no  doubt, 
illusive  representations  may  arise,  not  corresponding  with 
objects,  and  we  must  ascribe  this  illusion  either  to  images 
of  the  fancy  (dreams),  or  to  a  mistake  of  the  faculty  of 
judgment  (in  the  case  of  the  so-called  deceptions  of  the 

concerned   not   with  things  per  se,    but    only   with   phenomena — sc. 
representations. 


250-251]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    211 

senses).  To  avoid  these  illusions,  we  [proceed  according 
to  the  following  rule  :  that  which  is  connected  with  a  percep 
tion  according  to  empirical  laws  is  actual}-  But  this  illusion, 
as  well  as  the  caution  against  it,  affects  idealism,  as  well  as 
dualism,  since  it  only  concerns  the  form  of  experience.  In 
order  to  refute  empirical  idealism,  which  falsely  questions 
the  objective  reality  of  external  perceptions,  it  is  enough 
that  external  perception  should  immediately  prove  an 
actuality  in  space,  which  space,  although  it  be  the  mere 
form  of  representations,  nevertheless  possesses  objective 
reality  with  regard  to  all  external  phenomena,  which  are 
nothing  but  representations.  It  is  enough  to  show  that 
without  perception  even  invention  and  dreaming  would  be 
impossible;  so  that  our  external  senses,  as  far  as  the  [251] 
data  for  experience  are  concerned,  must  have  their  actual 
corresponding  object  in  space. 

The  man  who  denies  the  existence  of  matter  would  be 
the  dogmatical  idealist ;  he  who  doubts  it,  because  it  cannot 
be  proved,  would  be  the  sceptical  idealist  The  former 
theory  results  from  believing  that  there  are  contradictions 
in  the  possibility  of  there  being  matter  at  all — a  question 
with  which  we  are  not  yet  concerned.  The  following 
section,  on  dialectical  syllogisms,  which  portrays  the  reason 
in  internal  conflict  about  the  concepts  which  it  has  formed 
as  regards  the  possibility  of  what  belongs  to  connected  ex 
perience,  will  help  to  solve  that  difficulty  [of  dogmatic 
idealism].  But  the  sceptical  idealist,  who  only  attacks  the 
grounds  of  our  assertion,  and  declares  our  conviction  of  the 
existence  of  matter  to  be  insufficient — which  we  believe 
we  can  found  on  immediate  perception — such  a  man  is  a 
benefactor  to  human  reason,  since  he  compels  us,  even  in 

1  The  whole  discussion  turns  on  this,  the  second  postulate  of  empiri 
cal  thought.     Cf.  vol.  i.  p.  193.     B. 


212  APPENDIX  C  [251-252 

the  most  trifling  steps  of  ordinary  experience,  to  keep  wide 
awake,  and  not  to  annex  as  lawful  property  anything  that 
we  have  obtained  by  foul  means.  The  use  of  these  ideal 
istic  objections  is  now  quite  clear.  They  force  us,  if  we 
wish  to  avoid  confusion  in  our  most  ordinary  assertions,  to 
consider  all  perceptions,  whether  internal  or  external,  as 
merely  the  consciousness  of  what  belongs  to  our  sensi 
bility  ;  and  their  external  objects  not  as  things  per  se,  but 
only  representations,  of  which  we  are  as  immediately  con 
scious  as  of  any  other  representations.  They  are  only  called 
external  because  they  belong  to  that  sense  which  we  call 
the  external  sense,  of  which  the  intuition  is  space ;  and  this 
space  is  nothing  but  an  internal  species  of  representation, 
in  which  certain  perceptions  are  connected  with  one  another. 
[252]  Supposing  we  allowed  external  objects  to  be  things 
per  se,  it  would  be  absolutely  impossible  to  comprehend 
how  we  could  obtain  a  knowledge  of  their  actuality  without 
us,  since  we  rely  merely  on  the  representation  which  is 
within  us.  For,  since  no  one  can  have  a  sensation  without 
himself,  but  only  within,  the  whole  of  self-consciousness 
gives  us  nothing  but  our  own  determinations.  Con 
sequently  sceptical  idealism  compels  us  to  take  refuge  in 
the  only  course  still  open,  that  is,  in  the  ideality  of  all 
phenomena ;  and  this  we  expounded  in  the  transcendental 
Aesthetic,  independent  of  the  consequences,  which  we 
could  not  have  then  foreseen.  If  it  be  now  asked,  whether 
dualism  must  consequently  follow  in  psychology,  we  answer, 
certainly,  but  only  in  the  empirical  sense ;  that  is  to  say,  in 
the  connected  whole  of  experience,  matter,  as  substance  in 
phenomena,  is  actually  given  to  the  external  sense,  and  the 
thinking  Ego  is  also  given  to  the  internal  sense,  as  substance 
in  the  phenomenon ;  and  in  both  cases  phenomena  must 
be  connected  according  to  the  rules  which  this  Category 


252-253]    PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    213 

[of  substance]  introduces  into  the  connexion  of  our  external 
as  well  as  internal  representations.  But  if  we  desire  to 
widen,  as  is  usual,  the  notion  of  dualism,  and  take  it  in  its 
transcendental  sense,  then  neither  this  doctrine,  nor  Pneu- 
matisin  nor  Materialism,  which  oppose  it  from  different 
sides,  have  the  least  basis.  We  should  then  miss  the  proper 
determination  of  our  concepts,  and  consider  a  difference  in 
the  mode  of  representation  of  objects  (which  remain  un 
known  to  us,  as  to  what  they  are  in  themselves)  to  be  a 
difference  in  these  things  themselves.  /,  who  am  re 
presented  through  the  internal  sense  as  in  time,  and  objects 
without  me,  are  indeed  phenomena  totally  distinct  in  kind, 
but  need  not  therefore  be  thought  as  distinct  [253]  things. 
The  transcendental  object,  which  lies  at  the  basis  of  internal 
intuition  as  well  as  of  external  phenomena,  is  neither  matter, 
nor  a  thinking  being  per  se,  but  a  basis  of  phenomena  un 
known  to  us,  and  these  give  us  the  empirical  concept  as 
well  of  the  first  as  of  the  second. 

If  then,  as  the  present  Kritik  plainly  compels  us,  we 
keep  faithfully  to  the  rule  we  have  established,  not  to  push 
our  questions  any  further  than  possible  experience  has 
supplied  us  with  objects  for  them,  it  will  never  even  come 
into  our  heads  to  make  investigations  about  the  objects  of 
our  senses  as  to  what  they  may  be  in  themselves,  out  of 
relation  to  our  senses.  But  if  the  psychologist  takes  phe 
nomena  for  things  in  themselves,  he  may,  as  a  materialist, 
accept  for  his  doctrine  nothing  but  matter ;  or,  as  a  spirit 
ualist,  nothing  but  thinking  beings  (according  to  the  form 
of  our  internal  sense) ;  or  even,  as  a  dualist,  he  may  regard 
both  to  be  things  existing  per  se.  In  any  case  his  miscon 
ception  will  condemn  him  to  be  ever  speculating  how  that 
is  to  exist  per  se  which  is  no  thing  per  se,  but  only  the 
phenomenon  of  a  thing  in  general. 


2i4  APPENDIX  C  [253-254 

REFLECTION  CONCERNING  THE  WHOLE  OF  PURE  PSYCHO 
LOGY,  AS  AN  APPENDIX  TO  THESE  PARALOGISMS 

If  we  contrast  the  doctrine  of  the  soul  [psychology],  as  the 
physiology  of  the  internal  sense,  with  the  science  of  bodies — 
as  the  physiology  of  the  objects  of  the  external  senses — we 
shall  find  (in  addition  to  the  fact  that  in  both  we  know  a 
great  deal  empirically)  this  remarkable  difference,  that  in 
the  latter  science  much  can  be  cognised  a  \2^^\  priori  from 
the  mere  concept  of  an  extended  incompressible  being ; 
whereas  in  the  former,  from  the  concept  of  a  thinking 
being,  nothing  can  be  cognised  synthetically  a  priori. 
Because  although  both  are  phenomena,  yet  the  phenomenon 
presented  to  the  external  sense  has  something  permanent 1 
or  fixed,  which  gives  a  substratum  lying  at  the  basis  of 
changeable  determinations,  and  so  gives  us  a  synthetical 
concept,  namely,  that  of  space  and  a  phenomenon  in  it. 
Time,  on  the  contrary,  which  is  the  only  form  of  our  in 
ternal  intuition,  has  nothing  permanent  in  it;  so  that  it 
only  lets  us  know  the  change  of  determinations,  not  the 
determinable  object.  For  in  that  which  we  call  the  soul 
everything  is  in  a  continuous  flux,  and  nothing  is  permanent 
except  (if  you  will  have  it  so)  the  Ego,  which  is  perfectly 
simple,  merely  because  this  representation  has  no  content 
or  multiplicity ;  for  which  reason  it  seems  to  represent  or, 
I  should  rather  say,  indicate  a  simple  object.  In  order  to 
produce  a  pure  rational  cognition  of  the  nature  of  a  think 
ing  being  in  general,  this  Ego  should  be  an  intuition,  which, 
being  presupposed  in  all  thinking  (antecedent  to  any  experi- 

1  This  important  passage  again  anticipates  (almost  verbally)  the  re 
futation  of  idealism  of  the  Second  Edition.  It  shows  the  superior 
dignity  of  external  experience,  as  contrasted  with  internal,  in  affording 
us  data  for  science.  M. 


254-255]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    215 

ence),  should  give  us  synthetical  a  priori  propositions. 
But  this  Ego  is  just  as  little  an  intuition  as  it  is  a  concept 
of  any  object,  being  merely  the  form  of  consciousness  which 
can  accompany  both  kinds  of  representations,  and  raise 
them  to  cognitions,  so  far  as  something  else  is  given  in  in 
tuition  which  supplies  the  material  for  the  representation  of 
an  object.  Thus  all  rational  psy-  [255]  chology  falls  to  the 
ground,  being  a  science  surpassing  all  the  powers  of  the 
human  reason ;  and  there  remains  nothing  for  us  except  to 
study  our  souls  according  to  the  clue  given  by  experience, 
and  to  keep  within  the  limits  of  questions  not  exceeding 
the  content  which  can  possibly  be  given  by  internal  experi 
ence. 

But  though  this  science  gives  us  no  ampliative  know 
ledge,  but  is  composed  (when  it  attempts  to  do  so)  of 
nothing  but  paralogisms,  yet  we  cannot  deny  it  an  im 
portant  negative  use,  if  we  consider  it  as  nothing  but  a 
critical  treatment  of  our  dialectical  syllogisms,  and  indeed 
of  the  ordinary  natural  reason. 

Why  do  we  require  a  psychology  founded  upon  pure 
principles  of  the  Reason  only?  Without  doubt,  for  the 
particular  object  of  securing  our  thinking  self  from  the 
danger  of  Materialism.  This  is  done  by  the  rational 
notion  of  our  thinking  self,  which  we  have  set  forth ;  for, 
instead  of  there  being  any  danger  that  if  matter  were  taken 
away,  all  thinking — and  even  the  existence  of  thinking 
beings — would  consequently  vanish,  it  is  rather  clearly 
shown  that,  if  I  take  away  the  thinking  subject,  the  whole 
world  of  matter  must  vanish,  being  only  what  appears  in  the 
sensibility  of  our  subject,  as  a  species  of  its  representations. 

Having  proved  this,  I  am  of  course  not  in  the  least 
better  able  to  know  this  thinking  self  by  its  properties. 
Nay,  I  cannot  even  prove  its  existence  to  be  independent 


216  APPENDIX  C  [255-256 

of  the  transcendental  substratum  (whatever  it  is)  of  external 
phenomena;  for  both  are  to  me  unknown.  Yet,  as  it  is 
possible  for  me  to  find  a  reason  in  other  than  merely  specu 
lative  grounds  for  hoping  that  my  thinking  nature  will 
remain  permanent  in  the  midst  of  all  possible  changes  of 
state — as  this  is  possible,  though  I  [256]  openly  confess  my 
own  ignorance — an  important  point  is  gained,  since  I  am  able 
to  repel  the  dogmatical  attacks  of  speculative  opponents,  and 
show  them  that  they  can  never  know  more  of  the  nature  of 
my  thinking  subject,  to  enable  them  to  deny  the  possibility 
of  my  hopes,  than  I  can,  to  enable  me  to  maintain  them. 

On  this  transcendental  illusion  in  our  psychological 
concepts  are  based  three  additional  dialectical  questions, 
which  form  the  proper  object  of  rational  psychology,  and 
which  can  only  be  decided  by  the  foregoing  investigations. 
These  are  : — (a)  The  possibility  of  the  community  of  the 
soul  and  an  organic  body,  i.e.  the  animality  and  condition 
of  the  soul  in  this  life ;  (/3)  The  commencement  of  this 
community,  i.e.  the  state  of  the  soul  at  and  before  birth ; 
(y)  The  end  of  this  community,  i.e.  the  state  of  the  soul 
at  and  after  death  (the  question  of  immortality). 

Now  I  assert  that  all  the  difficulties  with  which  these 
questions  are  supposed  to  be  beset,  and  with  which,  used 
as  dogmatical  objections,  men  pretend  to  a  deeper  insight 
into  the  nature  of  things  than  can  be  obtained  by  plain 
common  sense — I  say  that  all  such  difficulties  are  based  on 
a  mere  delusion,  by  which  what  only  exists  in  our  thoughts 
is  hypostatised,  and,  without  its  quality  being  changed, 
assumed  to  be  an  actual  object  without  the  thinking  subject : 
for  example,  extension,  which  is  nothing  but  a  phenomenon, 
is  taken  for  a  property  of  external  things  existing  apart  from 
our  sensibility ;  and  motion  is  regarded  as  their  action,  tak 
ing  place  actually  in  itself,  even  apart  from  our  senses.  For 


256-257]  PARALOGISMS  OF'  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    217 

matter,  the  community  of  which  with  the  soul  raises  such 
difficulties,  is  nothing  but  a  mere  form,  or  a  certain  species, 
of  the  representation  of  an  unknown  object  through  that 
intui-[257]  tion  which  is  called  the  external  sense.     There 
may  indeed,  then,  be  something  without  us  to  which  this 
phenomenon,  which  we   call  matter,  corresponds;   but   in 
the  same  quality  as  phenomenon  it  is  not  without  us  [in 
the  transcendental  sense],  but  merely  a  thought  within  us, 
although  this  thought  (through  the  sense  just  mentioned) 
represents  it  as   to   be   found  without  us.1     Matter   then 
signifies,   not    a   species    of  substance,  thus    distinct    and 
heterogeneous  from  the  object  of  the  internal  sense  (soul), 
but  only  the  difference  in  kind  of  the  phenomena  of  objects 
(in  themselves  unknown  to  us),  whose  representations  we  call 
external,  as  compared  with  those  ascribed  to  the  internal 
sense,  even  though  the  former  belong  just  as  much  to  the 
thinking  subject  as  do  all  the  rest  of  our  thoughts.     They 
have,  however,  this  illusion  about  them,  that  as  they  re 
present  objects  in  space,  they  as  it  were  sever  themselves 
from  the  soul,  and  seem  to  exist  separate  from  it,  although 
space  itself,  in  which  they  are  intuited,  is  nothing  but  a 
representation,  the  object  of  which,  in   the   same  quality, 
cannot  be  met  at  all  without  the  soul.     Accordingly,  the 
question  is  no  longer  about  the  community  of  the  soul  with 
other  known  and  heterogeneous  substances  without  us,  but 
merely  concerning  the  connexion  of  the  representations  of 
the  internal  sense  with  the  modifications   of  our  external 
sensibility ;  and  how  it  is  that  these  are  connected  together 
according  to  constant  laws,  so  as  to  form  one  systematic 
experience. 

1  Here  is  a  plain  assertion  of  what  I  before  explained,  that  Kaiit  is 
refuting,  not  a  thing  per  se,  about  which  we  can  assert  nothing,  but  ' 
such  an  absurdity  as  a  noumenon  in  space.     M. 

II  Q 


218  APPENDIX  C  [257-259 

As  long  as  we  conjoin  in  experience  internal  and  [258]  ex 
ternal  phenomena  as  mere  representations,  we  find  nothing 
absurd  or  strange  in  the  community  of  both  species   of 
sense.     But  as  soon  as  we  hypostatise  external  phenomena, 
and  consider  them   no  longer  as  representations,  but  as 
things  existing  by  themselves  without  us,  in  the  same  quality  as 
they  are  in  us,  and  refer  their  activity,  which  they  exhibit  as 
phenomena  in  mutual  relation,  to  our  thinking  subject — if 
we  do  this,  the  effective  causes  without  us  assume  a  char 
acter  which  will  not  tally  with  their  effects  in  us,  because 
the  former  refers  merely  to  the  external,  the  latter  to  the  in 
ternal,  sense ;  and,  though  these  are  united  in  one  subject, 
they   are    still    very    different    in    kind.     Here,   then,   we 
have  no  external  effects,  except  changes  of  place,  and  no 
forces  except  tendencies  which  concern  relations  in  space 
as  their  effects.     But  within  us  the   effects  are  thoughts, 
among  which   no  relation  of  place,  motion,  figure,  or  any' 
space-determination  takes  place ;  and  we  lose  the  clue  to 
the    causes  altogether    in   the    effects,  which    they  should 
manifest  in  the  internal  sense.     But  we  ought  to  remember 
that  bodies  are  not  objects  per  se,  present  to  us,  but  a  mere 
appearance  of  nobody-knows-what-sort-of  unknown  object; 
that  motion  is  not  the  effect  of  this  unknown  cause,  but 
merely  the  appearance  of  its  influence  on  our  senses ;  con 
sequently,  that  both  are  not  anything  without  us,  but  mere 
representations  within   us.     It   follows,  that  it  is   not  the 
motion  of  matter  which  produces  representations  in  us,  but 
that  this  motion  itself  (and  matter  also,  which  makes  itself 
cognoscible  by  this  means)  is  mere  representation ;  and, 
finally,  that    the    whole    difficulty    we    have    conjured    up 
amounts  to  this  :  how,  and  through  what  cause,  the  repre 
sentations  of  our  sensibility  are  so  related,  that  those  which 
we   call   external  intuitions   can   [259]   be  represented  as 


259-260]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    219 

objects  without  us,  according  to  empirical  laws.  This 
question  by  no  means  contains  the  supposed  difficulty  of 
explaining  the  origin  of  the  representations  of  causes  which 
exist  without  us,  and  act  in  a  foreign  way — in  that  we  take 
the  appearances  of  an  unknown  cause  to  be  a  cause  without 
us — a  proceeding  which  can  breed  nothing  but  confusion. 
In  those  judgments  where  there  occurs  a  misconception 
rooted  in  long  habit,  it  is  not  possible  to  bring  the  correc 
tion  [of  the  error]  within  our  grasp,  in  the  same  degree  as 
in  those  other  cases  where  no  such  unavoidable  illusion 
confuses  our  concepts.  Hence  this  our  emancipation  of 
the  reason  from  sophistical  theories,  can  hardly  as  yet  have 
the  clearness  which  alone  produces  perfect  satisfaction. 

I   hope  to  make  the  matter  plainer  in   the  following 
way  : — 

All  objections  may  be  divided  into  dogmatical,  critical, 
and  sceptical.  A  dogmatical  objection  is  directed  against  a 
proposition ;  a  critical,  against  the  proof  of  a  proposition. 
The  former  presupposes  an  insight  into  the  nature  of  an 
object,  in  order  that  we  may  be  able  to  assert  the  reverse 
of  what  is  stated  concerning  the  object ;  such  a  proposition, 
then,  is  itself  dogmatical,  and  professes  to  know  more  of 
the  property  in  question  than  its  opponent.  The  critical 
objection,  as  it  never  touches  the  truth  or  falsity  of  the 
proposition,  and  only  attacks  the  proof,  does  not  require,  or 
pretend  to,  a  better  knowledge  of  the  object  than  the 
opposed  assertion ;  it  only  proves  the  assertion  groundless 
. — not  that  it  is  false.  The  sceptical  objection  opposes 
mutually  the  proposition  and  its  contradictory,  as  objections 
of  equal  value,  proposing  each  in  turn  as  a  dogma,  and  the 
other  as  the  objection  to  it,  and  so  appears  to  be  from 
opposite  sides  dog- [260]  matical,  in  order  to  destroy  com 
pletely  any  judgment  about  the  object.  Both  the  dog- 


220 


APPENDIX  C  [260-261 


matical  and  sceptical  objections  must  pretend  to  so  much 
insight  into  their  objects  as  is  necessary  to  assert  something 
of  them  affirmatively  or  negatively.  The  critical  alone 
differs  from  them,  in  that  it  overthrows  the  theory  by 
showing  that  something  worthless  or  merely  imaginary  has 
been  assumed  in  its  assertions,  and  by  removing  this  supposed 
foundation,  without  wishing  to  assert  anything  concerning 
the  nature  of  the  object. 

Now  according  to  the  ordinary  notions  of  our  reason  as 
to  the  community  in  which  our  thinking  subject  stands 
with  things  without  us,  we  are  dogmatical,  and  regard  them 
as  true  objects,  existing  independent  of  us,  according  to  a 
transcendental  dualism,  which  does  not  attribute  these  ex 
ternal  phenomena,  as  representations,  to  the  subject,  but 
transports  them,  just  as  we  get  them  from  sensuous  intuition, 
out  of  ourselves  as  objects,  which  this  dualism  separates 
completely  from  the  thinking  subject.  This  subreptio  is  the 
foundation  of  all  theories  as  to  the  community  between 
body  and  soul ;  and  the  question  is  never  raised  whether 
the  objective  reality  of  phenomena  be  certainly  true  :  this 
is  rather  assumed  as  conceded,  and  fallacious  reasonings 
started  as  to  its  explanation  or  conception.  The  three 
ordinary  systems  invented  to  meet  this  difficulty,  and  in 
deed  the  only  possible  ones,  are  those  of  physical  influence^ 
of  pre-established  harmony,  and  of  supernatural  assistance. 

The  two  latter  explanations  of  the  community  of  the 
soul  with  matter  are  based  upon  objections  to  the  first 
(which  is  the  representation  of  common  sense),  namely, 
that  what  appears  as  matter  cannot  by  immediate  influence 
be  the  cause  of  representations,  which  are  a  perfectly  [261] 
heterogeneous  sort  of  effect.  But  when  men  argue  in  this 
way  [it  is  clear  that]  they  cannot  unite  with  the  *  object  of 
the  external  sensibility'  the  notion  of  a  matter  which  is 


261-262]   PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    221 

only  phenomenon,  or  in  itself  mere  representation,  pro 
duced  by  any  sort  of  external  objects ;  for  if  they  held  this, 
they  would  have  said  that  the  representations  of  external 
objects  (phenomena)  cannot  be  external  causes  of  pheno 
mena  in  our  minds — a  senseless  objection,  for  it  never 
could  come  into  any  man's  head  to  consider  that  what  he 
had  already  acknowledged  to  be  mere  representation  was 
an  external  cause.  According  to  our  principles,  their  theory 
must  rather  attempt  to  show  that  the  true  (transcendental) 
object  of  our  external  senses  cannot  be  the  cause  of  those 
representations  (phenomena)  which  we  understand  by  the 
word  matter.  Now,  as  no  one  can  pretend  with  any 
reason  to  know  aught  of  the  transcendental  cause  of  the 
representations  of  our  external  senses,  their  assertion  is 
quite  groundless.  But,  if  the  pretended  correctors  of  the 
doctrine  of  physical  influence  regard  matter  as  such  (after 
the  usual  manner  of  transcendental  dualism)  to  be  a  thing 
per  se  (and  not  the  mere  phenomenon  of  an  unknown 
thing),  and  direct  their  objections  to  prove  that  such  an 
external  object,  which  exhibits  no  other  sort  of  causality 
except  motions,  can  never  be  the  efficient  cause  of  repre 
sentations,  but  that  a  third  being  must  interfere  to  produce, 
if  not  reciprocal  action,  at  least  correspondence  or  harmony 
between  both;  [if  these  theorists  take  this  course]  then 
their  refutation  of  their  opponents  must  begin  by  assuming 
the  [same]  TT/JWTOV  ^evSos  [as  the  theory]  of  physical  in 
fluence  in  their  own  dualism;  and  so  by  their  objection 
they  would  not  so  much  refute  Natural  Influence  as  refute 
their  own  dualistic  assumption.  For  [262]  all  difficulties 
which  beset  the  connexion  of  thinking  nature  with  matter 
arise,  without  exception,  merely  from  the  insinuation  of  the 
dualistic  representation,  that  matter  as  such  is  not  pheno 
menon,  or  a  mere  representation  of  the  mind,  to  which  an 


222  APPENDIX  C  [262-263 

unknown  object  corresponds,  but  is  that  object  in  itself,  as 
it  exists  without  us,  and  apart  from  all  sensibility. 

There  can,  then,  be  no  dogmatical  objection  made  to 
the  usually  accepted  Physical  Influence ;  for,  if  our 
opponent  assumes  that  matter  and  its  motion  are  mere 
phenomena,  and  therefore  themselves  mere  representa 
tions,  he  can  only  raise  this  difficulty,  that  the  unknown 
object  of  our  sensibility  cannot  be  the  cause  of  represent 
ations  in  us — a  thing  which  he  has  not  the  least  right 
to  assert,  because  nobody  can  tell  of  an  unknown  object 
what  it  can  or  cannot  do.  He  must,  however,  after  the 
proofs  given  above,  necessarily  concede  this  transcend 
ental  idealism,  so  far  as  he  does  not  openly  hypostatise 
representations,  and  place  them,  as  true  things,  without 
himself. 

But  a  well-founded  critical  objection  can  still  be  made  to 
the  common  doctrine  of  physical  influence.  Such  a  pre 
tended  community  between  two  kinds  of  substances — the 
thinking  and  the  extended — presupposes  a  gross  dualism, 
and  makes  the  latter,  which  are  nothing  but  mere  representa 
tions  of  the  thinking  subject,  into  things  existing  per  se. 
Physical  influence  thus  misconceived  may  then  be  com 
pletely  overthrown  by  showing  its  grounds  of  proof  to  be 
idle,  and  surreptitiously  obtained. 

The  notable  question  concerning  the  community  of 
that  which  thinks  and  that  which  is  extended — if  we 
discard  all  fictions — would  simply  come  to  this :  How 
external  intuition,  viz.  that  of  space  (the  occupation  of 
[263]  it,  figure  and  motion)  can  be  at  all  possible  in  a 
thinking  subject  1  But  to  this  question  no  man  can  ever 
find  an  answer ;  and  we  can  never  supply  this  gap  in  our 
knowledge,  but  only  indicate  it  by  ascribing  external 
phenomena  to  a  transcendental  object  (as  the  cause 


263-264]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    223 

of  this  sort  of  phenomena),  which  however  we  do  not 
know,  and  of  which  we  can  never  obtain  any  notion. 
In  all  problems  which  may  arise  in  the  field  of  experi 
ence  we  treat  these  phenomena  as  objects  per  se,  without 
concerning  ourselves  about  the  highest  ground  [or  condi 
tion]  of  their  possibility.  But,  if  we  transgress  this 
boundary,  the  concept  of  a  transcendental  object  becomes 
necessary. 

From  these  considerations  about  the  community  be 
tween  extended  and  thinking  beings  there  follows,  as 
an  immediate  consequence,  the  settlement  of  all  disputes 
or  objections  which  concern  the  condition  of  this  think 
ing  nature  before  the  community  (this  life),  or  after  its 
cessation  (in  death).  The  opinion  that  the  thinking 
subject  could  think  previous  to  any  community  with 
the  body  would  be  thus  expressed :  that  before  the  com 
mencement  of  this  sort  of  sensibility,  by  which  some 
thing  appears  to  us  in  space,  the  same  transcendental 
objects — which  in  our  present  condition  appear  as  bodies 
— may  have  been  intuited  quite  differently.  The  opinion 
that  the  soul,  after  the  cessation  of  all  community  with 
the  corporeal  world,  can  still  continue  to  think,  would 
announce  itself  in  this  form :  that  when  that  sort  of 
sensibility  ceases  by  which  transcendental — and  now 
wholly  unknown — objects  appear  to  us,  all  intuition  of  them 
may  not  consequently  vanish ;  and  that  it  is  quite  possible 
for  the  same  unknown  objects  to  continue  being  [264] 
cognised  by  the  subject,  though,  of  course,  no  longer  in  the 
quality  of  bodies.1 

1  To  assert  of  the  writer  of  the  preceding  argument  that  he  is  an 
absolute  idealist  is  surely  very  strange  criticism.  It  is  impossible 
to  conceive  a  more  distinct  and  official  refusal  to  accept  that  extreme 
doctrine.  M. 


224 


APPENDIX  C  [264-265 


Now  it  is  true  that  no  one  can  show  the  smallest 
foundation  for  such  an  assertion  from  speculative  prin 
ciples,  or  even  explain  its  possibility,  but  only  presup 
pose  it ;  yet  on  the  other  hand  no  one  can  oppose  it  with 
any  valid  dogmatical  objection.  For,  whoever  he  may 
be,  he  knows  no  more  of  the  absolute  and  internal  cause 
of  external  or  corporeal  phenomena  than  I  or  anybody 
else.  He  cannot  then  reasonably  pretend  to  know  on 
what  the  actuality  of  external  phenomena  depends  in  the 
present  state  (in  life),  nor  consequently,  that  the  condi 
tion  of  all  external  intuition,  or  even  that  the  thinking 
subject  itself,  must  cease  to  exist  after  this  state  (in 
death). 

The  whole  dispute,  then,  about  the  nature  of  our 
thinking  being  and  its  connexion  with  the  world  of 
matter,  merely  arises  from  our  supplying  the  gaps  in 
our  knowledge  by  paralogisms  of  the  Reason,  in  that  we 
make  our  thoughts  to  be  things,  and  hypostatise  them, 
whence  arises  an  imaginary  science,  both  as  regards  its 
affirmations  and  its  negations.  We  either  pretend  to 
know  something  of  objects,  of  which  nobody  has  the 
least  notion,  or  we  consider  our  own  representations  to 
be  objects,  and  so  become  involved  in  a  perpetual  circle 
of  ambiguities  and  contradictions.  Nothing  but  the 
sobriety  of  a  severe  but  fair  Kritik  can  free  us  from  this 
[265]  dogmatical  illusion,  which  enslaves  so  many  of  us 
in  fancied  happiness  under  theories  and  systems,  and  can 
restrict  all  our  speculative  claims  to  the  field  of  possible 
experience — not  indeed  by  ill-natured  ridicule  of  our 
many  failures,  nor  by  pious  laments  about  the  limits 
of  our  reason,  but  by  determining  these  limits  accurately 
according  to  fixed  principles.  By  this  means  its  'thus 
far,  and  no  farther,'  is  most  securely  fixed  at  those 


265-266]   PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    225 

pillars  of  Hercules  which  nature  herself  has  set  up,  in 
order  to  allow  the  voyage  of  our  reason  to  extend  only 
as  far  as  the  receding  coasts  of  experience  reach — coasts 
that  we  cannot  leave  without  venturing  into  a  boundless 
ocean,  which,  after  constant  illusions,  ultimately  compels 
us  to  give  up  as  hopeless  all  our  laborious  and  tedious 
efforts. 


We  still  owe  to  our  reader  a  distinct  and  general 
explanation  of  the  transcendental  and  yet  natural  illusion 
in  the  paralogisms  of  the  pure  Reason,  as  well  as  a 
justification  of  their  systematic  arrangement  running  parallel 
to  the  Categories.  This  we  could  not  undertake  at  the 
commencement  of  the  section  without  the  danger  of  be 
coming  obscure,  or  awkwardly  anticipating  ourselves.  We 
now  desire  to  discharge  this  obligation. 

We  can  consider  all  illusion  to  consist  in  this — that  the 
subjective  condition  of  thinking  is  taken  for  the  cognition 
of  the  object.  We  have  further  shown,  in  the  introduction 
to  the  transcendental  Dialectic,  that  pure  Reason  is 
merely  concerned  with  the  totality  of  the  synthesis  of 
the  conditions  of  a  given  conditioned.  [266]  Now,  as  the 
dialectical  illusion  of  the  pure  Reason  cannot  be  an 
empirical  illusion,  occurring  with  determinate  empirical 
cognition,  it  must  concern  the  conditions  of  thinking  gener 
ally,  and  there  can  be  only  three  cases  of  dialectical  use  of 
the  pure  Reason — 

1.  The    synthesis  of  the  conditions    of  a    thought    in 
general ; 

2.  The    synthesis     of    the     conditions     of    empirical 
thinking ; 

3.  The   synthesis   of  the  conditions  of  pure   thinking. 


226  APPENDIX  C  [266-267 

In  all  these  cases  the  pure  Reason  merely  employs 
itself  upon  the  absolute  totality  of  this  synthesis ;  that  is, 
upon  that  condition  which  is  itself  unconditioned.  On  this 
division  also  is  founded  the  threefold  transcendental  illusion, 
which  gives  rise  to  the  three  divisions  of  the  dialectic,  and 
affords  the  Idea  to  just  as  many  apparent  sciences  arising 
out  of  pure  Reason — to  transcendental  psychology,  cos 
mology,  and  theology.  We  are  here  only  concerned  with 
the  first. 

As  in  the  case  of  thinking  in  general  we  abstract  from 
all  relation  of  our  thought  to  any  object  (be  it  of  the  senses, 
or  of  the  pure  understanding),  the  synthesis  of  the  condi 
tions  of  a  thought  in  general  (No.  i)  is  not  at  all  objective, 
but  merely  a  synthesis  of  the  thought  with  the  subject, 
which  synthesis  is  falsely  held  to  be  a  synthetical  representa 
tion  of  an  object. 

But  it  follows  from  this,  that  the  dialectical  inference 
to  the  condition  of  all  thinking  in  general,  which  is 
itself  unconditioned,  does  not  make  a  mistake  as  to 
content  (for  it  abstracts  from  all  content  or  object),  but 
that  it  is  merely  false  as  to  form,  and  must  be  called  a 
paralogism. 

Furthermore,  as  the  condition  which  accompanies  [267] 
all  thinking  is  the  Ego,  in  the  general  proposition,  '  I 
think,'  Reason  must  be  concerned  with  this  condition,  so 
far  as  it  is  itself  unconditioned.  But  this  is  only  the  formal 
condition  or  logical  unity  of  every  thought,  in  which  I 
abstract  from  all  objects,  and  yet  it  is  represented  as  an 
object  which  I  think,  that  is,  the  Ego  and  its  unconditioned 
unity. 

Suppose  any  one  were  to  put  me  the  general  ques 
tion  :  Of  what  sort  of  nature  is  a  thinking  being  ?  I  do 
not  in  the  least  know  how  to  answer  the  question  a  priori, 


267-268]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    227 

because  the  answer  must  be  synthetical  (for  an  analytical 
answer  might,  perhaps,  explain  thinking,  but  could  not 
extend  our  knowledge  of  that  upon  which  thinking 
depends  as  to  its  possibility).  But  for  every  synthetical 
solution  intuition  is  necessary,  a  point  which  is  wholly 
passed  over  in  the  vague  problem  proposed.  It  is  equally 
impossible  to  answer,  in  all  its  generality,  the  question  : 
Of  what  nature  must  a  thing  capable  of  motion  be  ?  For 
incompressible  extension  (matter)  is  not  then  given 
to  us.  Yet,  although  I  know  no  answer  in  general  to 
that  sort  of  question,  it  appears  to  me  that  I  might  give 
one  in  the  special  case  of  the  proposition,  '  I  think,'  which 
expresses  consciousness.  For  this  Ego  is  the  first 
subject — that  is,  substance — it  is  simple,  etc.  But 
these  must  be  mere  empirical  judgments,  which,  at  the 
same  time,  could  not  contain  any  such  predicates  (which 
are  not  empirical),  without  a  general  rule  to  express 
the  conditions  of  the  possibility  of  thinking  them  in 
general,  and  this  a  priori?-  Thus,  what  I  [268]  at  first 
thought  so  feasible  (viz.  judgments  concerning  the  nature 
of  the  thinking  being,  and  this  from  pure  concepts), 
becomes  suspicious,  even  though  I  have  not  yet  discovered 
my  mistake. 

But  the  further  investigation  into  the  origin  of  these 
properties,  which  I  attribute  to  myself,  as  a  thinking  being 
in  general,  exposes  the  error.  They  are  nothing  more  than 
pure  Categories,  by  which  I  can  never  think  a  determined 
object,  but  only  the  unity  of  representations,  in  order  to 
determine  them  as  an  object.  Without  being  founded  on 
an  intuition,  the  Category  alone  can  never  provide  me  with 
a  concept  of  an  object ;  for  only  by  intuition  is  the  object 
given,  which  is  afterwards  thought  in  accordance  with  the 
1  Read  diese  for  dieses  and  konnten  for  konnte.  M. 


228  APPENDIX  C  [268-269 

Category.  If  I  assert  a  thing  to  be  a  substance  in  pheno 
menon,  the  predicates  of  its  intuition  must  have  been 
previously  given  to  me,  by  which  I  distinguish  the  per 
manent  from  the  changeable,  and  the  substratum  (thing  in 
itself)  from  what  is  merely  attached  to  it.  If  I  call  a  thing 
simple  in  phenomenon,  I  mean  by  this  that  its  intuition, 
indeed,  is  part  of  my  phenomena,  but  is  itself  not  divisible, 
etc.  But  if  anything  is  known  to  be  simple  only  in 
concept,  and  not  in  appearance,  then  I  have  actually  no 
knowledge  at  all  of  the  object,  but  only  of  my  concept, 
which  I  frame  about  something  in  general,  and  which  is 
not  capable  of  being  properly  intuited.  I  only  say  that 
I  think  a  thing  to  be  quite  simple,  because  I  can  actually 
say  nothing  more  about  it,  except  merely  that  it  is  some 
thing. 

Now,  mere  apperception  (Ego)  is  in  concept  substance, 
is  in  concept  simple,  etc.,  and  so  far  all  these  psychological 
dogmas  have  indisputable  truth.  Yet  what  we  want  to 
know  about  the  soul  is  not  at  all  [269]  discoverable  in  this 
way  ;  for,  since  none  of  these  predicates  are  valid  of  intuition, 
and  since  therefore  they  can  have  no  consequence  applicable 
to  objects  of  experience,  they  are  quite  void.  For  the  above 
mentioned  concept  of  substance  does  not  teach  me  that  the 
soul  continues  to  exist  by  itself,  nor  that  it  is  a  part  of  the 
external  intuitions,  which  cannot  itself  be  further  divided, 
and  which  can,  consequently,  neither  originate  nor  pass 
away  by  any  changes  of  nature  :  all  of  which  are  properties 
which  would  make  the  soul  cognoscible  to  me  in  the 
connexion  of  experience,  and  might  throw  some  light  upon 
its  origin  and  future  state.  But  when  I  assert  by  the  mere 
Category,  that  the  soul  is  a  simple  substance,  it  is  clear  that 
as  the  mere  concept  of  substance  contains  nothing  but  this, 
that  a  thing  shall  be  represented  as  a  subject  per  se,  without 


269-270]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    229 

also  being  the  predicate  of  another,  [it  is  clear,  I  say  that] 
from  this  concept  no  permanence  follows,  and  that  the 
attribute  of  simplicity  could  certainly  not  add  this  per 
manence  ;  so  that  we  are  not  in  the  least  informed  of  what 
might  happen  to  the  soul  in  the  changes  of  the  world.  If 
we  could  be  told  that  it  is  a  simple  part  of  matter,  we  might, 
owing  to  what  experience  tells  us,  infer  permanence,  and 
along  with  its  simple  nature  indestructibility.  But  about 
this,  the  concept  of  the  Ego  in  the  psychological  first  prin 
ciple  (I  think)  tells  us  not  a  word. 

The  following  is  the  reason  that  the  being  which  in  us 
imagines  it  can  cognise  itself  by  pure  Categories,  and 
indeed  by  those  which  express  absolute  unity  under  each  of 
their  classes.  Apperception  is  itself  the  ground  of  the 
possibility  of  the  Categories,  which  on  their  side  represent 
nothing  but  the  synthesis  of  the  manifold  in  intuition,  so  far 
as  it  has  unity  in  apper- [270]  ception.  Hence,  self-con 
sciousness  in  general  is  the  representation  of  that  which  is 
the  condition  of  all  unity,  and  yet  itself  unconditioned. 
Of  the  thinking  Ego,  then,  or  soul  (which  represents  itself 
as  substance,  simple,  numerically  identical  at  all  times, 
and  the  correlation  of  all  existence,  from  which  all  other 
existence  must  be  inferred),  we  may  say,  that  it  does  not 
cognise  itself  through  the  Categories,  but  rather  the  Cate 
gories,  and  through  them  all  objects  in  the  absolute  unity 
of  apperception,  viz.  through  itself.  It  is  indeed  quite 
plain  that  what  I  must  presuppose  in  order  to  cognise  any 
object  at  all,  I  cannot  also  cognise  as  an  object ;  and  that 
the  determining  self  (thinking)  is  distinguished  from  the 
determinable  self  (the  thinking  subject),  as  cognition  is 
from  objects.  Still  nothing  is  more  natural  or  seductive 
than  the  illusion  of  considering  the  unity  in  the  synthesis  of 
thoughts  to  be  a  perceived  unity  in  the  subject  of  these 


23o  APPENDIX  C  [270-271 

thoughts.     We  might  call  it  the  subreption  of  hypostatised 
consciousness  (apperceptionis  substantiates}^ 

If  we  wish  to  give  its  logical  name  to  the  paralogism  in 
the  dialectical  syllogisms  of  rational  psychology,  so  far  as 
their  premises  are  in  themselves  true,  it  may  be  called  a 
sophisma  figura  dictionis,  in  which  the  major  premiss  makes 
merely  a  transcendental  use  of  the  Category  with  reference 
to  its  condition,  but  the  minor  premiss  and  conclusion  make 
of  the  same  Category  an  empirical  use  with  reference  to  the 
soul,  which  has  been  subsumed  under  this  condition.  So, 
for  example,  in  the  paralogism  of  simplicity  the  concept  of  sub 
stance  is  [2  7 1]  a  pure  intellectual  concept,  which,  without  the 
condition  of  sensuous  intuition,  is  merely  of  transcendental, 
that  is,  of  no,  use.  But  in  the  minor  premiss  the  very  same 
concept  is  applied  to  the  object  of  all  internal  experience, 
yet  without  first  establishing  and  laying  down  as  a  basis  the 
condition  of  its  application  in  concrete^  that  is,  its  per 
manence  ;  hence,  there  is  here  an  empirical,  though 
illegitimate,  application  made  of  it.  In  order  to  show  the 
systematic  connexion  of  all  these  dialectical  assertions  in  a 
fallacious  psychology,  as  connected  in  the  pure  Reason — 
that  is,  in  order  to  show  its  completeness — observe  that  the 
apperception  is  carried  through  all  the  classes  of  the  Cate 
gories,  but  only  applied  to  those  concepts  of  the  under 
standing  which  in  each  [class]  supply  to  the  rest  the  basis 
of  unity  in  a  possible  perception,  and  these  are — subsistence, 
reality,  unity  (not  plurality),  and  existence;  only  that 
Reason  here  represents  them  as  the  conditions  of  the 
possibility  of  a  thinking  being,  which  conditions  are 
themselves  conditioned.  Consequently,  the  soul  cog 
nises  itself  as — 

1  I  cannot  but  think  that  Mansel's  theory  of  self  being  presented  as 
substance  is  here  clearly  refuted.  M. 


271-272]  PARALOGISMS  OF  RATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY    231 

1.  The  unconditioned  unity  of  Relation,  that  is,  not  as 
inhering,  but  subsisting; 

2.  The  unconditioned  unity  of  Quality -,  that  is,  not  as 
a  real  whole,  but  simple  ; 1 

3.  The  unconditioned  unity  in  plurality  in  time,  that 
is,  not  in  different  times  numerically  different,  but  as  one 
and  the  very  same  subject ; 

4.  The   unconditioned  unity  of  existence  in  space,  that 
[272]  is,  not  as  the  consciousness  of  several  things  without 
it,  but  only  of  its  own  existence,  and  of  other  things,  on 
the  contrary,  merely  as  its  representations. 

Reason  is  the  faculty  of  principles.  The  assertions  of 
pure  psychology  do  not  contain  empirical  predicates  of  the 
soul,  but  those  which,  if  they  occur,  should  determine  the 
object  per  se  independent  of  experience,  that  is,  through 
the  pure  Reason.  They  must,  then,  be  fairly  based  upon 
principles  and  universal  notions  of  thinking  natures  in 
general.  Instead  of  this,  we  find  that  the  single  represent 
ation,  /  am,  governs  the  whole  of  it,  which,  because  it 
expresses  the  pure  formula  of  all  my  experience  (indetermin 
ately),  announces  itself  as  an  universal  proposition,  valid  for 
all  thinking  beings ;  and,  as  it  is  single  from  every  point  of 
view,  assumes  the  appearance  of  an  absolute  unity  in  the 
conditions  of  thinking  in  general,  and  so  extends  itself 
further  than  possible  experience  can  reach. 

1  How  the  simple  here  again  corresponds  to  the  Category  of  Reality, 
I  am  as  yet  unable  to  show  ;  but  it  will  be  explained  upon  the  occasion 
of  another  rational  use  of  the  very  same  concept.  [Simplicity  corre 
sponds  to  unconditioned  Reality,  for  the  reality  of  a  composite  whole 
depends  on  that  of  each  of  its  parts.  B.] 


[273]   APPENDIX    D 

[Part  of  the  gt/i  Section  of  the  Antinomy  of  the  Pure 
Reason .] 

POSSIBILITY  OF  CAUSALITY  THROUGH  FREE 
DOM  IN  HARMONY  WITH  THE  UNIVERSAL 
LAW  OF  NATURAL  NECESSITY 

That  in  an  object  of  the  senses  which  is  not  itself  pheno 
menon,  I  term  intelligible.  If,  accordingly,  an  object 
which  must  be  regarded  as  a  phenomenon  in  the  sensuous 
world  possesses  in  itself  [or  per  se]  also  a  faculty  which  is 
not  an  object  of  sensuous  intuition,  but  by  means  of  which 
it  is  capable  of  being  the  cause  of  phenomena,  the  causality 
of  this  being  may  be  regarded  from  two  different  points  of 
view.  The  causality  may  be  considered  to  be  intelligible, 
as  regards  its  action — the  action  of  a  thing  in  itself — and 
also  sensible,  as  regards  its  effects  as  a  phenomenon  belonging 
to  the  sensuous  world. 

We  should,  accordingly,  have  to  form  both  an  empirical 
concept  of  the  faculty  of  such  a  subject,  as  well  as  an 
intellectual  concept  of  its  causality,  which  both  occur 
together  in  one  and  the  same  effect.  This  twofold  manner 
of  thinking  the  faculty  of  a  sensuous  object  does  not  run 


273-274]  INTELLIGIBLE  AND  EMPIRICAL  CHARACTERS  233 

counter  to  any  of  the  concepts  which  we  ought  to  form  of 
phenomena,  or  of  possible  experience;  for  as  phenomena 
— not  being  things  in  themselves — must  have  a  transcend 
ental  [274]  object  as  a  foundation,  which  determines  them 
as  mere  representations,  there  seems  to  be  no  reason  why 
we  should  not  ascribe  to  this  transcendental  object,  in  ad 
dition  to  the  property  by  means  of  which  it  appears,  a 
causality  which  is  not  a  phenomenon,  although  its  effects  are 
observed  in  the  world  of  phenomena. 

But  every  effective  cause  must  possess  a  character — that 
is  to  say,  a  law  of  its  causality — without  which  it  would  not 
be  a  cause  at  all.  Accordingly,  in  a  subject  of  the  world 
of  sense  we  should  have  an  empirical  character,  which 
guaranteed  that  its  actions,  as  phenomena,  stand  in  complete 
and  harmonious  connexion,  conformably  to  unvarying  natural 
laws,  with  all  other  phenomena,  and  can  be  deduced  from 
these  as  conditions ;  and  that  they  do  thus,  in  connexion 
with  these,  constitute  members  of  a  single  series  in  the 
order  of  nature. 

In  the  second  place,  we  should  be  obliged  to  concede 
to  it  an  intelligible  character  also,  by  means  of  which  it  is 
indeed  the  cause  of  those  actions  as  phenomena,  but  which 
is  not  itself  a  phenomenon,  nor  subordinate  to  the  conditions 
of  the  world  of  sense.  The  former  may  be  termed  the 
character  of  the  thing  as  a  phenomenon;  the  latter,  the 
character  of  the  thing  as  a  thing  per  se. 

Now  this  acting  subject  would,  in  its  intelligible  character, 
be  subject  to  no  conditions  of  time;  for  time  is  only  a 
condition  of  phenomena,  and  not  of  things  in  themselves. 
No  action  would  begin  or  cease  to  be  in  this  subject;  it 
would,  consequently,  be  free  from  the  law  of  all  determina 
tion  of  time — of  all  change — namely,  that  everything  which 
happens  must  have  a  cause  in  the  phenomena  (of  the 

II  R 


234 


APPENDIX  D  [274-276 


preceding  state).  In  a  word,  the  [275]  causality  of  the  sub 
ject,  in  so  far  as  it  is  intelligible,  would  not  form  a  part  of  the 
series  of  empirical  conditions  which  necessitated  the  event 
in  the  world  of  sense.  Again,  this  intelligible  character  of 
a  thing  could  indeed  never  be  immediately  cognised,  because 
we  can  perceive  nothing  except  so  far  as  it  appears,  but  it 
must  still  be  thought  in  accordance  [or  analogy]  with  the 
empirical  character ;  just  as  we  find  ourselves  compelled  in 
a  general  way,  to  place,  in  thought,  a  transcendental  object  at 
the  basis  of  phenomena,  although  we  know  nothing  of  what 
it  is  in  itself. 

Accordingly,  as  to  its  empirical  character,  this  subject, 
being  a  phenomenon,  would  be  subject  to  the  causal  nexus 
in  all  the  laws  of  its  determination  ;  and  it  would  so  far  be 
nothing  but  a  part  of  the  world  of  sense,  of  which  the  effects 
would  follow  without  fail  from  nature,  like  every  other 
phenomenon.  When  influenced  by  external  phenomena — 
when  cognised  through  experience  in  its  empirical  character, 
i.e.  in  the  law  of  its  causality — all  its  actions  must  be 
explicable  according  to  natural  laws,  and  all  the  requisites 
for  their  complete  and  necessary  determination  must  occur 
in  possible  experience. 

By  virtue  of  its  intelligible  character,  on  the  other  hand 
(although  we  possess  only  the  general  notion  of  this 
character),  the  subject  must  be  regarded  as  free  from  all 
sensuous  influences,  and  from  all  phenomenal  determination. 
Moreover,  as  nothing  happens  in  this  subject — as  far  as  it 
is  a  noumenon — and  there  does  not,  consequently,  exist  in 
it  any  change  demanding  the  dynamical  determination  of 
time,  and  for  the  same  reason  no  connexion  with  phenomena 
as  its  causes — this  active  being  must,  in  its  actions,  be  so 
far  free  [276]  from  and  independent  of  natural  necessity, 
for  this  necessity  exists  only  in  sensibility.  It  would  be 


276-277]  INTELLIGIBLE  AND  EMPIRICAL  CHARACTERS  235 

quite  correct  to  say  that  it  originates  or  begins  its  effects  in 
the  world  of  sense  from  itself  without  the  action  beginning 
in  itself.  We  should  not  be  in  this  case  affirming  that  these 
sensuous  effects  began  to  exist  of  themselves,  because  they 
are  always  determined  by  prior  empirical  conditions,  but 
only  by  virtue  of  the  empirical  character  (which  is  the 
phenomenon  of  the  intelligible  character),  and  are  possible 
only  as  constituting  a  continuation  of  the  series  of  natural 
causes.  And  thus  nature  and  freedom — each  in  its  complete 
signification — can  meet,  without  contradiction  or  disagree 
ment,  in  the  same  action,  according  as  it  is  compared  with 
its  intelligible  or  sensible  cause. 

FURTHER  ELUCIDATION  OF  THE  COSMOLOGICAL  IDEA 
OF  FREEDOM  IN  CONNECTION  WITH  THE  UNIVERSAL 
LAW  OF  NATURAL  NECESSITY. 

I  have  thought  it  advisable  to  lay  before  the  reader  at 
first  a  mere  sketch  of  the  solution  of  this  transcendental 
problem,  in  order  to  enable  him  to  form  with  greater  ease 
a  clear  notion  of  the  course  which  Reason  must  adopt  in 
the  solution.  I  shall  now  proceed  to  exhibit  the  several 
momenta  of  this  solution,  and  to  consider  them  in  their 
order.  The  natural  law,  that  everything  which  happens 
must  have  a  cause ;  that  the  causality  of  this  cause,  that  is, 
the  action  (which  cannot  always  have  existed,  but  must  be 
itself  an  event,  for  it  precedes  in  [277]  time  some  effect 
which  has  then  originated},  must  have  its  cause  among 
phenomena  by  which  it  is  determined ;  and  consequently, 
that  all  events  are  empirically  determined  in  an  order 
of  nature — this  law,  I  say,  which  lies  at  the  foundation 
of  the  possibility  of  experience  and  of  a  connected  system 
of  phenomena,  or  nature,  is  a  law  of  the  understanding, 


236  APPENDIX  D  [277-278 

from  which  no  departure,  and  to  which  no  exception,  can 
be  admitted.  For  to  except  even  a  single  phenomenon 
from  its  operation  is  to  exclude  it  from  the  sphere  of 
possible  experience,  and  make  it  a  mere  fiction  of  thought, 
or  phantom  of  the  brain. 

Thus  we  are  obliged  to  acknowledge  the  existence  of  a 
chain  of  causes,  in  the  regress  of  which,  however,  absolute 
totality  cannot  be  found.  But  we  need  not  detain  ourselves 
with  this  difficulty ;  for  it  has  already  been  removed  in  our 
general  discussion  of  the  antinomy  of  the  Reason,  when  it 
attempts  to  reach  the  unconditioned  in  the  series  of  phe 
nomena.  If  we  permit  ourselves  to  be  deceived  by  the 
deception  of  transcendental  realism,  we  shall  find  that 
neither  nature  nor  freedom  remain.  Here  the  only  question 
is :  Whether,  recognising  nothing  but  natural  necessity  in 
the  whole  series  of  events,  it  is  possible  to  consider  the 
same  effect  as  on  the  one  hand  an  effect  of  nature,  and  on 
the  other  an  effect  of  freedom ;  or,  whether  these  two 
species  of  causality  are  absolutely  contradictory. 

Among  the  causes  in  phenomena  there  can  surely  be 
nothing  which  could  commence  a  series  absolutely,  and  of 
itself.  Every  action,  as  phenomenon,  so  far  as  it  produces 
an  event,  is  itself  an  event  or  occurrence  presupposing 
another  state,  in  which  its  cause  is  to  be  found.  [278]  Thus 
everything  that  happens  is  but  a  continuation  of  the  series ; 
and  no  commencement,  starting  of  itself,  is  here  possible. 
The  actions  of  natural  causes  are  accordingly  themselves 
effects,  and  presuppose  causes  preceding  them  in  time. 
An  original  action — an  action  by  which  something  happens 
which  was  not  previously — is  beyond  the  causal  connexion 
of  phenomena. 

Now,  is  it  necessary  that,  granting  all  effects  to 
be  phenomena,  the  causality  of  their  cause,  which  (cause) 


278-279]  INTELLIGIBLE  AND  EMPIRICAL  CHARACTERS  237 

is  itself  a  phenomenon,  must  belong  to  the  empirical  world  ? l 
Is  it  not  rather  possible  that,  although  for  every  effect  in  the 
phenomenon  a  connexion  with  its  cause  according  to  the  laws 
of  empirical  causality  is  required,  this  empirical  causality 
may  be  itself  an  effect  of  a  causality  not  empirical,  but 
intelligible — its  connexion  with  natural  causes  remaining, 
nevertheless,  intact? 

Such  a  causality  would  be  considered,  in  reference  to 
phenomena,  as  the  original  action  of  a  cause  which  is  in  so 
far,  therefore,  not  phenomenal,  but,  as  regards  this  faculty, 
intelligible,  although  the  cause  must  at  the  same  time,  as  a 
link  in  the  chain  of  nature,  be  regarded  as  belonging  to 
the  sensuous  world. 

A  belief  in  the  causality  of  phenomena  among  each 
other  is  necessary,  if  we  are  required  to  look  for  and  give 
an  account  of  the  natural  conditions  of  natural  [279]  events; 
that  is  to  say,  their  causes  in  phenomena.  This  being 
admitted  as  unexceptionably  valid,  the  requirements  of  the 
understanding,  which  recognises  nothing  but  nature,  and  is 
entitled  to  it,  are  satisfied ;  and  our  physical  explanations 
may  proceed  in  their  regular  course,  without  let  or 
hindrance. 

But  it  is  no  stumbling-block  in  the  way,  even  assuming 
it  to  be  a  mere  fiction,  to  admit  that  there  are  some2 
natural  causes  which  have  a  faculty  that  is  only  intelligible, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  not  determined  to  action  by  empirical 

1  The  reader  will  observe  that  Kant  uses  the  word  cause  for  the  total 
subject  of  the  causality  both  noumenal  and  phenomenal,  and  distinctly 
speaks  of  the  causality — even  the  intelligible  causality — of  a  thing  as 
different  from  the  thing  (cause)  itself.     Here  he  differs  from  Hamilton, 
and,  I  must -add,  agrees  with  common  sense.     M. 

2  This   is   a   distinct   statement,    and   opposed    to   Kuno   Fischer's 
account  of  the  matter,  Comm.  p.  243.     Fischer  substitutes  all  for  Kant's 
some.     M. 


238  APPENDIX  D  [279-280 

conditions,  but  solely  upon  grounds  of  the  understanding ; 
so,  however,  that  the  action  in  the  phenomenon  of  this 
cause  must  be  in  accordance  with  all  the  laws  of  empirical 
causality. 

Thus  the  acting  subject,  as  a  causa  phenomenon,  would 
continue  to  preserve  a  complete  connexion  with  nature  and 
natural  conditions ;  and  only  the  noumenon  of  this  subject 
(with  all  its  causality  in  the  phenomenon)  would  contain 
certain  conditions,  which,  if  we  ascend  from  the  empirical 
to  the  transcendental  object,  must  be  regarded  as  merely 
intelligible.  For  if  we  attend,  in  our  inquiries  with  regard 
to  causes  in  the  world  of  phenomena,  to  the  directions  of 
nature  alone,  we  need  not  trouble  ourselves  about  what 
sort  of  basis  is  conceived  for  these  phenomena  and  their 
natural  connexion  in  the  transcendental  subject  (which  is 
empirically  unknown  to  us). 

This  intelligible  ground  of  phenomena  does  not  concern 
empirical  questions.  Perhaps  it  has  only  to  do  [2  80]  with 
thinking  in  the  pure  understanding;  and,  although  the 
effects  of  this  thinking  and  acting  of  the  pure  understanding 
are  discoverable  in  phenomena,  these  phenomena  must, 
nevertheless,  be  capable  of  a  full  and  complete  explanation, 
in  accordance  with  natural  laws.  And  in  this  case  we 
attend  solely  to  their  empirical  (as  the  highest  ground  of 
explanation),  and  omit  all  consideration  of  their  intelligible, 
character  (which  is  the  transcendental  cause  of  the  former), 
as  completely  unknown,  except  in  so  far  as  it  is  indicated 
by  the  latter  as  its  sensuous  symbol. 

Now  let  us  apply  this  to  experience.  Man  is  one  of  the 
phenomena  of  the  sensuous  world,  and  so  far  also  one  of 
the  natural  causes,  the  causality  of  which  must  be  regulated 
by  empirical  laws.  As  such,  he  must  possess  an  empirical 
character,  like  all  other  objects  of  nature.  We  remark  this 


280-281]  INTELLIGIBLE  AND  EMPIRICAL  CHARACTERS  239 

empirical  character  in  his  effects,  which  reveal  the  presence 
of  certain  powers  and  faculties.  If  we  consider  inanimate 
or  merely  brute  nature,  we  can  discover  no  reason  for 
conceiving  any  faculty  to  be  determined  otherwise  than  in 
a  purely  sensuous  manner. 

But  man,  to  whom  the  rest  of  nature  reveals  herself  only 
through  sense,  cognises  himself  (not  only  by  his  senses, 
but)  also  through  mere  apperception ;  and  this  in  actions 
and  internal  determinings,  which  he  cannot  regard  as 
sensuous  impressions.  He  is  thus  to  himself  on  the  one 
hand  indeed  a  phenomenon ;  but  on  the  other,  in  respect 
of  certain  faculties,  a  purely  intelligible  object — intelligible, 
because  its  action  cannot  be  ascribed  to  the  receptivity  of 
sensibility.  We  call  these  faculties  understanding  and 
Reason. 

The  latter,  especially,  is  in  a  peculiar  manner  distinct 
[281]  from  all  empirically-conditioned  faculties;  for  it  con 
siders  its  objects  merely  in  accordance  with  Ideas,  and  by 
means  of  these  determines  the  understanding,  which  then 
proceeds  to  make  an  empirical  use  of  its  concepts,  which 
indeed  are  also  pure.1 

1  The  remainder  of  the  discussion  is  rendered  much  less  inaccurately 
by  Mr.  Meiklejohn  (pp.  338  jy<?.);  I  have,  therefore,  not  thought  it 
necessary  to  repeat  it  here.  M. 


THE    END 


Printed  by  R.  &  R.  CLARK,  Edinbitrgh. 


WORKS  by  the  Rev.  J.  P.  MAHAFFY,  M.A.,  D.D., 

FELLOW  OF  TRINITY  COLLEGE,  DUBLIN. 


Social    Life    in   Greece,   from    Homer    to    Menander. 
Sixth  Edition,  enlarged.     Crown  8vo.     95. 

The  Athenceum  says  : — "  Mr.  Mahaffy  has,  in  this  little  volume,  given 
us  the  results  of  considerable  reading,  and  has  given  them  in  a  form  which 
is  both  pleasant  and  interesting.  .  .  .  No  omission  greatly  detracts  from 
the  merits  of  a  book  so  fresh  in  its  thought  and  so  independent  in  its 
criticism.  .  .  .  One  feels  that  the  author  is  no  mere  compiler,  but  an 
original  thinker  ;  and  whether  we  agree  with  his  conclusions  or  not,  we 
at  least  respect  the  boldness  and  straightforwardness  with  which  he  holds 
his  own." 

Greek  Life  and  Thought,  from  the  Age  of  Alexander 
to  the  Roman  Conquest.     Crown  8vo.      i  zs.  6d. 

The  Academy  says  : — "  These  studies  of  Greek  life  and  thought  may  be 
regarded  as  complementary  to  more  than  one  of  Professor  Mahaffy's  other 
volumes  upon  Greek  affairs.  They  carry  further  the  account  of  Social  Life 
in  Greece ;  they  take  note  of  authors  later  than  the  point  at  which  the 
History  of  Greek  Literature  ends  ;  and  they  supply  the  domestic  and 
literary  features  necessary  to  body-out  the  brilliant  sketch  of  Alexander's 
Empire.  Mr.  Mahaffy  vindicates,  in  an  eloquent  introduction,  the  im 
portance  of  his  subject.  .  .  .  The  subject  is  a  grand  one,  and  the  author's 
opportunity  is  the  better  because  the  subject  has  been  comparatively 
neglected.  The  political  and  social  experiments  of  the  time  ;  the  spread 
of  Greek  culture  necessary  for  the  future  of  humanity  ;  the  actual  achieve 
ments  in  architecture  and  sculpture,  in  poetry  and  in  painting — these  things 
arouse  instantly  the  interest  of  the  historian  and  the  artist,  while  the 
philosopher  will  be  curious  to  see  how  Mr.  Mahaffy  justifies  his  favourable 
opinion  of  the  morality  and  the  daily  life.  This  splendid  subject  has  now 
found  an  English  historian  competent  to  do  it  justice." 

The  Guardian  says  : — " ...  At  his  own  immediate  subject  Mr. 
Mahaffy  has  worked  with  much  skill  and  care.  It  is  pleasant  to  visit 
Alexandria,  Antioch,  and  Pergamon  in  his  company,  and  to  make  acquaint 
ance  with  their  kings,  their  poets,  and  their  philosophers.  We  see  what 
kind  of  literature,  what  kind  of  philosophy,  grew  up  in  a  very  artificial 
and  conscious  age,  an  age  which,  as  Mr.  Mahaffy  does  not  fail  often  to 
remind  us,  has  so  very  much  in  common  with  modern  Europe." 

Rambles    and    Studies    in   Greece.     With    Illustrations. 
Third  Edition,  revised  and  enlarged.     Crown  8vo.     los.  6d. 

The  Sf.  James's  Gazette  says  : — "  It  is  unnecessary  to  praise  this  book, 
which  the  public  has  already  decided  to  be  one  of  the  best  of  its  kind. 
The  present  edition  is  enriched  with  a  good  deal  of  additional  information." 

i]  M/CMILLAN  AND  CO.,  LONDON. 


WORKS  by  the  Rev.  J.  P.  MAHAFFY,  M.A.,  D.D, 

FELLOW  OF  TRINITY  COLLEGE,  DUBLIN. 


The  Art  of  Conversation,  The  Principles  of.     Second 
Edition,  revised.     Crown  8vo.     45.  6d. 

The  Guardian  says  : — "  The  result  is  a  book  which  has  abundance  of 
shrewd  remarks." 

The  Saturday  Review  says  : — "  Full  of  shrewd  observation.  .  .  .  Most 
of  his  rules  and  recommendations  are  aimed  at  promoting  conversation, 
and  directing  it  into  the  right  channel." 

The  Nation  (New  York)  says:  —  "Independently  of  these  general 
questions,  which  must  be  touched  upon  of  necessity  in  a  volume  of  first 
principles,  Mr.  Mahaffy's  dissertation  is  a  very  practical  and  useful  one. 
His  treatment  is  light,  but  thorough,  and  he  pursues  his  subject  with  un 
flagging  spirit  through  all  its  compass.  Hosts  and  guests  may  equally 
learn  from  him." 

Euripides.       l8mo.       IS.  6d.  [Classical  Writers. 

The  Academy  says  : — "  No  better  book  on  the  subject  has  previously 
been  written  in  English.  Mr.  Mahaffy  is  scholarly  and  not  pedantic, 
appreciative  and  yet  just." 

The  Cambridge  Review  says  : — "We  can  recommend  this  work  to  all 
our  readers  ;  it  is  very  interesting,  and,  what  is  more  important,  very 
suggestive." 

Greek  Antiquities.     Illustrated.      i8mo.      is. 

[Literature  Primers. 

The  Saturday  Review  says: — "We  can  conceive  no  handbook  of  a 
hundred  pages  which  furnishes  readers  with  so  much  light  upon  the  civil 
and  domestic  life  of  the  Greeks." 

The  Decay  of  Modern  Preaching.     An  Essay.     Crown 
8vo.     35.  6d. 

The  Saturday  Review  says: — "The  work  is  clever  and  sensible  in 
most  of  its  criticisms  and  suggestions." 

The  Church  of  England  Pulpit  says  : — "  It  is  an  excellent  little  book." 
The  Scotsman  says  : — "  It  is  thoroughly  well  worth  reading." 


Euripides.  Hippolytus.  Edited,  with  Introduction  and 
Notes,  by  J.  P.  MAHAFFY  and  J.  B.  BURY.  Fcap.  8vo. 
3S.  6d.  [Classical  Series. 

MACMILLAN  AND  CO.,  LONDON. 


MESSRS.  MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

With  upwards  of  Eighty  Illustrations. 
Sketches  from  a  Tour  through  Holland  and  Germany. 

By  J.  P.  MAHAFFY  and  J.  E.  ROGERS.     With  Illustrations  by  J.  E. 
ROGERS.     Extra  Crown  8vo.     IDS.  6d. 

This  is  an  account  of  a  tour  through  some  of  the  less  known  towns  in 
Holland,  Central  Germany,  and  along  the  Baltic  Coast.  The  titles  of 
chapters  are  as  follows  :  Preamble ;  Down  the  Thames ;  Dordrecht ; 
Leiden  and  Haarlem  ;  About  the  Zuider  Zee — Enkhuizen  ;  Miscellaneous 
Gleanings  ;  Central  Germany,  Brunswick — Romanesque  Churches  ;  Helm- 
stedt — Hildesheim  ;  Marburg — Fulda  ;  In  the  Country;  Some  Baltic 
Towns — Wismar  ;  Liibeck — Liineberg — Hamburg  ;  On  the  Way  Home. 

The  Saturday  Review  says  :  "  If  this  tour  through  Holland  and  part  of 
Germany  does  not  largely  increase  our  knowledge  of  those  countries,  it  is,  at 
any  rate,  a  very  pleasant  and  amusing  book." 

The  Scotsman  says  :  "A  cheery  and  delightful  book  of  travel.  .  .  .  All 
the  book  is  bright  and  animated.  The  sketches  join  with  the  text  in  giving 
just  notions  of  bits  of  mediaeval  architecture.  The  text  itself  is  richer.  Art, 
history,  economics,  social  habits,  surface-politics,  fashions  in  dress,  philology 
and  the  inaptitude  of  the  Dutch  vulgar  to  understand  their  own  language  when 
spoken  with  a  possible  brogue — these  and  a  thousand  others  are  the  topics  of 
the  text.  They  are  treated  most  lightly  and  pleasantly.  The  book  will  be 
heartily  enjoyed  by  all  its  readers." 

The  Glasgow  Herald  says  :  ' '  This  entertaining  and  most  readable  volume 
is  in  no  sense  a  guide  book.  It  does  not  attempt  to  catalogue  and  label  every 
sight  and  every  curiosity  for  the  benefit  of  intending  travellers.  It  contains 
the  jottings  of  two  intelligent,  cultured,  and  observant  tourists  who,  in  addition 
to  all  that  Baedeker  and  Murray  point  out,  have  seen  much  that  is  interesting, 
but  too  often  overlooked,  and  is,  indeed,  just  such  a  book  as  will  delight  those 
who  already  possess  some  acquaintance  with  the  places  described  in  it." 

The  Manchester  Guardian  says  :  ' '  Any  one  who  is  doubting  where  he  had 
better  go  for  his  next  continental  holiday  will  find  this  book  pregnant  of  sug 
gestion.  .  .  .  On  the  whole,  the  book  is  slight — a  record  of  casual  impressions, 
though  the  impressions  of  exceptionally  intelligent  and  open-eyed  observers. 
It  is,  however,  distinctly  readable,  and  the  architectural  sketches  of  interesting 
bits  in  old  towns  like  Alkmar,  or  Hildesheim,  or  Liibeck,  or  Rostock,  greatly 
add  to  its  attractiveness." 

The  Aberdeen  Journal  says  :  "  The  book  contains  a  large  fund  of  informa 
tion  both  valuable  and  interesting,  especially  to  archaeologists  devoted  to  the 
study  of  Gothic  and  Renaissance  architecture.  .  .  .  Mr.  Mahaffy  and  Mr. 
Rogers  have  indeed  given  their  readers  a  treat." 

Truth  says  :  "  It  is  a  brightly  written  and  beautifully  illustrated  book." 

The  Field  says  :  "This  book  contains  an  interesting  account  of  many 
places  in  Holland  and  Central  Germany,  outside  the  track  usually  followed  by 
the  English  or  American  tourist  .  .  .  the  illustrations  are  remarkably  good 
.  .  .  the  account  given  by  the  authors  of  the  people  and  the  things  in  general 
that  came  under  their  notice  are  all  pleasantly,  and  in  many  instances  amus 
ingly,  written  ;  and  their  remarks  on  the  political  state  of  Germany  at  the 
present  time  are  well  worthy  of  notice." 

The  Dublin  Evening  Mail  says  :  "  Of  all  the  books  this  season  has  pro 
duced  within  measurable  distance  of  modest  pockets,  this  sketch-book  deserves 
the  palm." 

MACMILLAN   AND   CO.,  LONDON. 


6160 


MESSRS.  MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 


Critique  of  Pure  Reason  by  Immanuel  Kant.  In  commemoration  of 
the  Centenary  of  its  first  Publication.  Translated  into  English  by  F.  MAX  M()LLER. 
With  an  Historical  Introduction  by  LUDWIG  NOIRE.  2  vols.  Demy  8vo.  i6s.  (sold 
separately)  each.  Vol.  I.  HISTORICAL  INTRODUCTION,  by  LUDWIG  NOIRE,  etc.,  etc. 
Vol.  II.  CRITIQUE  OF  PURE  REASON.  Translated  by  F.  MAX  MULLER. 

Of  Professor  Max  Miiller's  translation  of  the  "Critique  of  Pure  Reason"  the  Times 
says  :  "Through  this  translation  Kant's  work  has  for  the  first  time  become  international 
— the  common  property  of  the  whole  world." 

The  Academy  says  :  "  A  worthy  piece  of  work.  Its  language  is  generally  vigorous 
and  direct,  and  it  preserves  a  considerable  fidelity  to  the  turns  and  structure  of  the  original. 
...  It  may  convey  to  English  readers,  as  few  translations  from  the  German  do,  a  real 
idea  of  the  original  work.  It  will  bring  them  nearer  Kant's  own  thought." 

The  British  Quarterly  Review  says  :  "  Professor  Max  Muller  has  here  performed  a 
service  for  his  great  countryman  which,  as  years  roll  by,  will  be  more  and  more  recog 
nised  by  our  own  countrymen  as  having  supplied  a  new  starting-point  for  their  thought- 
lives,  and  given  them  the  means  of  accounting  to  themselves  for  experience." 

Nature  says  :  "  Professor  Max  Miiller  has  given  to  students  of  philosophy  what  they 
did  not  possess  before,  and  that  is  far  superior  to  the  ordinary  work  of  this  sort.  His 
offering  is  indeed  what  it  intended  to  be,  a  fitting  commemoration  of  the  centenary  of  the 
date  in  which  was  published  the  treatise  which  was  destined  to  revolutionise  philosophy. 
A  faithful  and  literal  translation  of  that  treatise  is  a  book  for  which  hejwill  not  find  the 
public  ungrateful  to  him." 

The  Nation  (New  York)  says:  "It  generally  gives  Kant's  meaning  with  superior 
precision.  It  is  no  inconsiderable  advantage  that  the  language  from  which,  and  that 
into  which,  Professor  Max  Miiller  translates,  are  both  alike  his  own.  To  English  readers 
his  work  is  sure  to  bring  Kant  home  better  than  anything  we  had  before  ;  and  even  those 
who  read  German  readily  will  frequently  gain  something  by  looking  up  Max  Miiller's 
understanding  of  an  obscure  passage.  His  translation  '  serves  in  some  passages  even  as 
a  commentary  on  the  original.'  For  the  first  time,  too,  we  have  the  '  Critique'  as  it  was 
originally  written." 

The  Athenceum  says :  "  Professor  Max  Miiller's  translation  is  the  best  English 
version  of  the  whole  '  Kritik,'  .  .  .  and  it  is  likely  to  hold  that  position  for  some  time." 


Outlines  of  Cosmic  Philosophy,  Based  on  the  Doctrine  of  Evolution, 
with  Criticisms  on  the  Positive  Philosophy.  By  JOHN  FISKE,  M.A.,  LL.B.,  for 
merly  Lecturer  on  Philosophy  at  Harvard  University.  2  vols.  8vo.  253. 

Recent  British  Philosophy.  A  Review,  with  Criticisms,  including  some 
Comments  on  Mr.  Mill's  Answer  to  Sir  William  Hamilton.  By  DAVID  MASSON, 
M.A.,  Professor  of  Rhetoric  and  English  Literature  in  the  University  of  Edinburgh. 
Third  Edition,  revised  and  enlarged.  Crown  8vo.  6s. 

Moral  and  Metaphysical  Philosophy.      By  FREDERICK    DENISON 

MAURICE.  Vol.  I. — Ancient  Philosophy  and  the  First  to  the  Thirteenth  Centuries. 
Vol.  II.— Fourteenth  Century  and  the  French  Revolution,  with  a  Glimpse  into  the 
Nineteenth  Century.  Fourth  Edition.  2  vols.  8vo.  i6s. 

The  First  Book  of  the  Metaphysics.  Translated  into  English  Prose, 
with  marginal  Analysis  and  Summary  of  each  Chapter.  By  a  Cambridge  Graduate. 
8vo.  5s. 

The  Politics.  Translated,  with  an  Analysis  and  Critical  Notes.  By  J. 
E.  C.  WELLDON,  M.A.,  Fellow  of  King's  College;  Cambridge,  and  Head  Master  of 
Harrow.  Crown  8vo.  Second  Edition.  IDS.  6d. 

The  Rhetoric.     By  the  same  Translator.     Crown  8vo.     7s.  6d. 


MACMILLAN   AND   CO.,  LONDON. 


Kant,  Immanuel  B 

2779 

Kant's  critical  phil.  for      .M27 ". 
English  readers  vol.2