Skip to main content

Full text of "Kant's Prolegomena to any future metaphysics"

See other formats


'S  PROLEGOMENA 


PAUL  CARUS 


KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA 


TO  ANY  FUTURE  METAPHYSICS 


EDITED  IN  ENGLISH 

BY 

DR.  PAUL  CARUS 


REPRINT  EDITION 


WITH  AN  ESSAY  ON  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY,  AND 

OTHER  SUPPLEMENTARY  MATERIAL 

FOR  THE  STUDY  OF  KANT 


CHICAGO     :::    LONDON 

THE  OPEN  COURT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY 
1949 


TRANSLATION  COPYRIGHTED 
BY 

THE  OPEN  COURT  PUBLISHING  Co 
1902. 


Printed  in  the  United  States  of  America 
By  PAQUIN  PRINTERS,  Chicago 


PUBLISHERS'  PREFACE. 

T7"  ANT'S  Prolegomena,^  although  a  small  book,  is  indubitably 
•^  the  most  important  of  his  writings.  It  furnishes  us  with  a 
key  to  his  main  work,  The  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  ;  in  fact,  it 
is  an  extract  containing  all  the  salient  ideas  of  Kant's  system.  It 
approaches  the  subject  in  the  simplest  and  most  direct  way,  and 
is  therefore  best  adapted  as  an  introduction  into  his  philosophy. 
For  this  reason,  The  Open  Court  Publishing  Company  has  deemed 
it  advisable  to  bring  out  a  new  edition  of  the  work,  keeping  in 
view  its  broader  use  as  a  preliminary  survey  and  explanation  of 
Kant's  philosophy  in  general.  In  order  to  make  the  book  useful 
for  this  broader  purpose,  the  editor  has  not  only  stated  his  own 
views  concerning  the  problem  underlying  the  Prolegomena  (see 
page  167  et  seq.),  but  has  also  collected  the  most  important  ma 
terials  which  have  reference  to  Kant's  philosophy,  or  to  the  recep 
tion  which  was  accorded  to  it  in  various  quarters  (see  page  241  et 
seq.).  The  selections  have  not  been  made  from  a  partisan  stand 
point,  but  have  been  chosen  with  a  view  to  characterising  the  atti 
tude  of  different  minds,  and  to  directing  the  student  to  the  best 
literature  on  the  subject. 

It  is  not  without  good  reasons  that  the  appearance  of  the 
Critique  of  Ptire  Reason  is  regarded  as  the  beginning  of  a  new 
era  in  the  history  of  philosophy ;  and  so  it  seems  that  a  compre 
hension  of  Kant's  position,  whether  we  accept  or  reject  it,  is  indis 
pensable  to  the  student  of  philosophy.  It  is  not  his  solution  which 

1  Prolegomena  means  literally  prefatory  or  introductory  remarks.  It  is 
the  neuter  plural  of  the  present  passive  participle  of  TrpoAe'-yeiy,  to  speak  before^ 
i  e.,  to  make  introductory  remarks  before  beginning  one's  regular  discourse. 


IV  PREFACE. 

makes  the  sage  of  Konigsberg  the  initiator  of  modern  thought,  but 
his  formulation  of  the  problem. 


The  present  translation  is  practically  new,  but  it  goes  without 
saying  that  the  editor  utilised  the  labors  of  his  predecessors,  among 
whom  Prof.  John  P.  Mahaffy  and  John  H.  Bernard  deserve  special 
credit.  Richardson's  translation  of  1818  may  be  regarded  as  super 
seded  and  has  not  been  consulted,  but  occasional  reference  has 
been  made  to  that  of  Prof.  Ernest  Belfort  Bax.  Considering  the 
difficulties  under  which  even  these  translators  labored  we  must 
recognise  the  fact  that  they  did  their  work  well,  with  painstaking 
diligence,  great  love  of  the  subject,  and  good  judgment.  The  editor 
of  the  present  translation  has  the  advantage  of  being  to  the  manor 
born ;  moreover,  he  is  pretty  well  versed  in  Kant's  style  ;  and 
wherever  he  differs  from  his  predecessors  in  the  interpretation  of 
a  construction,  he  has  deviated  from  them  not  without  good  rea 
sons.  Nevertheless  there  are  some  passages  which  will  still  re 
main  doubtful,  though  happily  they  are  of  little  consequence. 

As  a  curiosum  in  Richardson's  translation  Professor  Mahaffy 
mentions  that  the  words  wider  sinnig  gewundene  Schnecken, 
which  simply  means  "symmetric  helices,"1  are  rendered  by 
"snails  rolled  up  contrary  to  all  sense"— a  wording  that  is  itself 
contrary  to  all  sense  and  makes  the  whole  paragraph  unintelli 
gible.  We  may  add  an  instance  of  another  mistake  that  misses 
the  mark.  Kant  employs  in  the  Appendix  a  word  that  is  no  longer 
used  in  German.  He  speaks  of  the  Cento  der  Metaphystk  as  having 
neue  Lappen  and  einen  verdnderten  Zuschnitt.  Mr.  Bax  trans 
lates  Cento  by  "body,"  Lappen  by  "outgrowths,"  and  Zuschnitt 
by  "figure."  His  mistake  is  perhaps  not  less  excusable  than 
Richardson's  ;  it  is  certainly  not  less  comical,  and  it  also  destroys 
the  sense,  which  in  the  present  case  is  a  very  striking  simile. 

1  Mahaffy  not  incorrectly  translates  "spirals  winding  opposite  ways," 
and  Mr.  Bax  follows  him  verbatim  even  to  the  repetition  of  the  footnote. 


PREFACE.  V 

Cento  is  a  Latin  word1  derived  from  the  Greek  aivrpuv*  meaning 
"a  garment  of  many  patches  sewed  together,"  or,  as  we  might 
now  say,  "a  crazy  quilt." 

*        *        » 

In  the  hope  that  this  book  will  prove  useful,  The  Open  Court 
Publishing  Company  offers  it  as  a  help  to  the  student  of  philosophy. 

p.  c. 

IThe  French  centon  is  still  in  use. 

iffeVrpup,  (l)  one  that  bears  the  marks  of  the  ntvrpov,  goad;  a  rogue,  (2)  a 
patched  cloth  ;  (3)  any  kind  of  patchwork,  especially  verses  made  up  of  scraps 
from  other  authors. 


TABLE  OF  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

Kant's  Prolegomena 1-163 

Essay  on  Kant's  Philosophy  by, Dr.  Paul  Carus.     (With  Por 
traits  of  Kant  and  Garve) 167-240 

Supplementary  Materials  for  the  Study  of  Kant's  Life  and 
Philosophy  : 

Introductory  Note 243 

Kant's  Life  and  Writings.      (After  Windelband) 245 

The  Critique  of  Practical  Reason  and  the  Critique  of 

Judgment.     (After  Weber) 250 

Kant's  Views  on  Religion.     (After  Schwegler) 258 

Kant  and  Materialism.     (After  Lange) 261 

Kant  and  Deism.     (After  Heinrich  Heine.)    With  Fac 
simile  of   the   Title-page  of   the   Critique  of  Pure 

Reason 264 

The  Kantian  Philosophy.   (After  Arthur  Schopenhauer)  279 
Hostile  Estimate  of  Kant  by  a  Swedenborgian.     (After 

Theodore  F.  Wright) 283 

Facsimile  and  Translation  of  a  Letter  of  Kant  to  His 

Brother 285 

Chronology  of  Kant's  Life  and  Publications.     (After 

Paulsen) 287 

Index  to  Kant's  Prolegomena 293 

Index  to  the  Article  on  Kant's  Philosophy 299 


KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


INTRODUCTION. 


'T^HESE  Prolegomena  are  destined  for  the  use,  not 
JL  of  pupils,  but  of  future  teachers,  and  even  the 
latter  should  not  expect  that  they  will  be  serviceable 
for  the  systematic^exposition  of  a  ready-made  science, 
but  merely  for  the  discovery  of  the  science  itself. 

There  are  scholarly  men,  to  whom  the  history  of 
philosophy  (both  ancient  and  modern)  is  philosophy 
itself;  for  these  the  present  Prolegomena  are  not 
written.  They  must  wait  till  those  who  endeavor  to 
draw  from  the  fountain  of  reason  itself  have  com 
pleted  their  work ;  it  will  then  be  the  historian's  turn 
to  inform  the  world  of  what  has  been  done.  Unfor 
tunately,  nothing  can  be  said,  which  in  their  opinion 
has  not  been  said  before,  and  truly  the  same  proph 
ecy  applies  to  all  future  time;  for  since  the  human 
reason  has  for  many  centuries  speculated  upon  innu 
merable  objects  in  various  ways,  it  is  hardly  to  be  ex 
pected  that  we  should  not  be  able  to  discover  anal 
ogies  for  every  new  idea  among  the  old  sayings  of 
past  ages. 

My  object  is  to  persuade  all  those  who  think  Meta 
physics  worth  studying,  that  it  is  absolutely  necessary 
to  pause  a  moment,  and,  neglecting  all  that  has 
been  done,  to  propose  first  the  preliminary  question, 
*  Whether  such  a  thing  as  metaphysics  be  at  all  pos 
sible?' 


2  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

If  it  be  a  science,  how  comes  it  that  it  cannot, 
like  other  sciences,  obtain  universal  and  permanent 
recognition  ?  If  not,  how  can  it  maintain  its  preten 
sions,  and  keep  the  human  mind  in  suspense  with 
hopes,  never  ceasing,  yet  never  fulfilled?  Whether 
then  we  demonstrate  our  knowledge  or  our  ignorance 
in  this  field,  we  must  come  once  for  all  to  a  definite 
conclusion  respecting  the  nature  of  this  so-called  sci 
ence,  which  cannot  possibly  remain  on  its  present 
footing.  It  seems  almost  ridiculous,  while  every  other 
science  is  continually  advancing,  that  in  this,  which 
pretends  to  be  Wisdom  incarnate,  for  whose  oracle 
every  one  inquires,  we  should  constantly  move  round 
the  same  spot,  without  gaining  a  single  step.  And 
so  its  followers  having  melted  away,  we  do  not  find 
men  confident  of  their  ability  to  shine  in  other  sciences 
venturing  their  reputation  here,  where  everybody,  how 
ever  ignorant  in  other  matters,  may  deliver  a  final 
verdict,  as  in  this  domain  there  is  as  yet  no  standard 
weight  and  measure  to  distinguish  sound  knowledge 
from  shallow  talk. 

After  all  it  is  nothing  extraordinary  in  the  elabora 
tion  of  a  science,  when  men  begin  to  wonder  how  far 
it  has  advanced,  that  the  question  should  at  last 
occur,  whether  and  how  such  a  science  is  possible? 
Human  reason  so  delights  in  constructions,  that  it  has 
several  times  built  up  a  tower,  and  then  razed  it  to 
examine  the  nature  of  the  foundation.  It  is  never  too 
late  to  become  wise;  but  if  the  change  comes  late, 
there  is  always  more  difficulty  in  starting  a  reform. 

The  question  whether  a  science  be  possible,  pre 
supposes  a  doubt  as  to  its  actuality.  But  such  a  doubt 
offends  the  men  whose  whole  possessions  consist  of 
**~'r  si  pposed  jewel ;  hence  he  who  raises  the  doubt 


INTRODUCTION.  3 

must  expect  opposition  from  all  sides.  Some,  in  the 
proud  consciousness  of  their  possessions,  which  are 
ancient,  and  therefore  considered  legitimate,  will  take 
their  metaphysical  compendia  in  their  hands,  and  look 
down  on  him  with  contempt ;  others,  who  never  see 
anything  except  it  be  identical  with  what  they  have 
seen  before,  will  not  understand  him,  and  everything 
will  remain  for  a  time,  as  if  nothing  had  happened  to 
excite  the  concern,  or  the  hope,  for  an  impending 
change. 

Nevertheless,  I  venture  to  predict  that  the  inde 
pendent  reader  of  these  Prolegomena  will  not  only 
doubt  his  previous  science,  but  ultimately  be  fully 
persuaded,  that  it  cannot  exist  unless  the  demands 
here  stated  on  which  its  possibility  depends,  be  satis 
fied  ;  and,  as  this  has  never  been  done,  that  there  is, 
as  yet,  no  such  thing  as  Metaphysics.  But  as  it  can 
never  cease  to  be  in  demand,1 — since  the  interests  of 
common  sense  are  intimately  interwoven  with  it,  he 
must  confess  that  a  radical  reform,  or  rather  a  new 
birth  of  the  science  after  an  original  plan,  are  un 
avoidable,  however  men  may  struggle  against  it  for  a 
while. 

Since  the  Essays  of  Locke  and  Leibnitz,  or  rather 
since  the  origin  of  metaphysics  so  far  as  we  know  its 
history,  nothing  has  ever  happened  which  was  more 
decisive  to  its  fate  than  the  attack  made  upon  it  by 
David  Hume.  He  threw  no  light  on  this  species  of 
knowledge,  but  he  certainly  struck  a  spark  from 

1  Says  Horace  : 

"  Rusticus  expectat,  dum  defluat  amnis,  at  illc 

Labitur  et  labetur  in  omne  volubilis  aevum;  " 
14  A  rustic  fellow  waiteth  on  the  shore 
For  the  river  to  flow  away, 
But  the  river  flows,  and  flows  on  as  before, 
And  it  flows  forever  and  aye." 


4  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

which  light  might  have  been  obtained,  had  it  caught 
some  inflammable  substance  and  had  its  smouldering 
fire  been  carefully  nursed  and  developed. 

Hume  started  from  a  single  but  important  concept 
in  Metaphysics,  viz. ,  that  of  Cause  and  Effect  (in 
cluding  its  derivatives  force  and  action,  etc.).  He 
challenges  reason,  which  pretends  to  have  given  birth 
to  this  idea  from  herself,  to  answer  him  by  what  right 
she  thinks  anything  to  be  so  constituted,  that  if  that 
thing  be  posited,  something  else  also  must  necessarily 
be  posited  ;  for  this  is  the  meaning  of  the  concept  of 
cause.  He  demonstrated  irrefutably  that  it  was  per 
fectly  impossible  for  reason  to  think  a  priori  and  by 
means  of  concepts  a  combination  involving  necessity.. 
We  cannot  at  all  see  why,  in  consequence  of  the  ex 
istence  of  one  thing,  another  must  necessarily  exist, 
or  how  the  concept  of  such  a  combination  can  arise 
a  priori.  Hence  he  inferred,  that  reason  was  alto 
gether  deluded  with  reference  to  this  concept,  which 
she  erroneously  considered  as  one  of  her  children, 
whereas  in  reality  it  was  nothing  but  a  bastard  of  im 
agination,  impregnated  by  experience,  which  sub 
sumed  certain  representations  under  the  Law  of  Asso 
ciation,  and  mistook  the  subjective  necessity  of  habit 
for  an  objective  necessity  arising  from  insight.  Hence 
he  inferred  that  reason  had  no  power  to  think  such 
combinations,  even  generally,  because  her  concepts 
would  then  be  purely  fictitious,  and  all  her  pretended 
a  priori  cognitions  nothing  but  common  experiences 
marked  with  a  false  stamp.  In  plain  language  there 
is  not,  and  cannot  be,  any  such  thing  as  metaphysics 
at  all.1 

1  Nevertheless  Hume  called  this  very  destructive  science  metaphysics 
and  attached  to  it  great  value.     Metaphysics  and  morals  [he  declares  in  the 


INTRODUCTION.  5 

However  hasty  and  mistaken  Hume's  conclusion 
may  appear,  it  was  at  least  founded  upon  investiga 
tion,  and  this  investigation  deserved  the  concentrated 
attention  of  the  brighter  spirits  of  his  day  as  well  as 
determined  efforts  on  their  part  to  discover,  if  pos 
sible,  a  happier  solution  of  the  problem  in  the  sense 
proposed  by  him,  all  of  which  would  have  speedily 
resulted  in  a  complete  reform  of  the  science. 

But  Hume  suffered  the  usual  misfortune  of  meta 
physicians,  of  not  being  understood.  It  is  positively 
painful  to  see  how  utterly  his  opponents,  Reid,  Os 
wald,  Beattie,  and  lastly  Priestley,  missed  the  point 
of  the  problem  ;  for  while  they  were  ever  taking  for 
granted  that  which  he  doubted,  and  demonstrating 
with  zeal  and  often  with  impudence  that  which  he 
never  thought  of  doubting,  they  so  misconstrued  his 
valuable  suggestion  that  everything  remained  in  its 
old  condition,  as  if  nothing  had  happened. 

The  question  was  not  whether  the  concept  of 
cause  was  right,  useful,  and  even  indispensable  for 
our  knowledge  of  nature,  for  this  Hume  had  never 
doubted ;  but  whether  that  concept  could  be  thought 
by  reason  a  priori,  and  consequently  whether  it  pos 
sessed  an  inner  truth,  independent  of  all  experience, 
implying  a  wider  application  than  merely  to  the  ob 
jects  of  experience.  This  was  Hume's  problem.  It 
was  a  question  concerning  the  origin,  not  concerning 
the  indispensable  need  of  the  concept.  Were  the  former 

fourth  part  of  his  Essays]  are  the  most  important  branches  of  science;  math 
ematics  and  physics  are  not  nearly  so  important.  But  the  acute  man  merely 
regarded  the  negative  use  arising  from  the  moderation  of  extravagant  claims 
of  speculative  reason,  and  the  complete  settlement  of  the  many  endless  and 
TMiblesome  controversies  that  mislead  mankind.  He  overlooked  the  posi 
tive  injury  which  results,  if  reason  be  deprived  of  its  most  important  pro 
spects,  which  can  alone  supply  to  the  will  the  highest  aim  for  all  its  en 
deavor. 


6  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

decided,  the  conditions  of  the  use  and  the  sphere  of 
its  valid  application  would  have  been  determined  as 
a  matter  of  course. 

But  to  satisfy  the  conditions  of  the  problem,  the 
opponents  of  the  great  thinker  should  have  penetrated 
very  deeply  into  the  nature  of  reason,  so  far  as  it  is 
concerned  with  pure  thinking, — a  task  which  did  not 
suit  them.  They  found  a  more  convenient  method  of 
!>eing  defiant  without  any  insight,  viz.,  the  appeal  to 
;ommon  sense.  It  is  indeed  a  great  gift  of  God,  to  pos 
sess  right,  or  (as  they  now  call  it)  plain  common 
sense.  But  this  common  sense  must  be  shown  prac 
tically,  by  well-considered  and  reasonable  thoughts 
and  words,  not  by  appealing  to  it  as  an  oracle,  when 
no  rational  justification  can  be  advanced.  To  appeal 
to  common  sense,  when  insight  and  science  fail,  and 
no  sooner — this  is  one  of  the  subtile  discoveries  ot 
modern  times,  by  means  of  which  the  most  superficial 
ranter  can  safely  enter  the  lists  with  the  most  thorough 
thinker,  and  hold  his  own.  But  as  long  as  a  particle 
of  insight  remains,  no  one  would  think  of  having  re 
course  to  this  subterfuge.  For  what  is  it  but  an  ap 
peal  to  the  opinion  of  the  multitude,  of  whose  ap 
plause  the  philosopher  is  ashamed,  while  the  popular 
charlatan  glories  and  confides  in  it?  I  should  think 
that  Hume  might  fairly  have  laid  as  much  claim  to 
common  sense  as  Beattie,  and  in  addition  to  a  critical 
reason  (such  as  the  latter  did  not  possess),  which 
keeps  common  sense  in  check  and  prevents  it  from 
speculating,  or,  if  speculations  are  under  discussion, 
restrains  the  desire  to  decide  because  it  cannot  satisfy 
itself  concerning  its  own  arguments.  By  this  means 
alone  can  common  sense  remain  sound.  Chisels  and 
hammers  may  suffice  to  work  a  piece  of  wood,  but  for 


INTRODUCTION.  7 

steel-engraving  we  require  an  engraver's  needle.  Thus 
common  sense  and  speculative  understanding  are 
each  serviceable  in  their  own  way,  the  former  in  judg 
ments  which  apply  immediately  to  experience,  the 
latter  when  we  judge  universally  from  mere  concepts, 
as  in  metaphysics,  where  sound  common  sense,  so 
called  in  spite  of  the  inapplicability  of  the  word,  has 
no  right  to  judge  at  all. 

I  openly  confess,  the  suggestion  of  David  Hume 
was  the  very  thing,  which  many  years  ago  first  inter 
rupted  my  dogmatic  slumber,  and  gave  my  investiga 
tions  in  the  field  of  speculative  philosophy  quite  a 
new  direction.  I  was  far  from  following  him  in  the 
conclusions  at  which  he  arrived  by  regarding,  not  the 
whole  of  his  problem,  but  a  part,  which  by  itself  can 
give  us  no  information.  If  we  start  from  a  well- 
founded,  but  undeveloped,  thought,  which  another 
has  bequeathed  to  us,  we  may  well  hope  by  continued 
reflection  to  advance  farther  than  the  acute  man,  to 
whom  we  owe  the  first  spark  of  light. 

1  therefore  first  tried  whether  Hume's  objection 
could  not  be  put  into  a  general  form,  and  soon  found 
that  the  concept  of  the  connexion  of  cause  and  effect 
was  by  no  means  the  only  idea  by  which  the  under 
standing  thinks  the  connexion  of  things  a  priori,  but 
rather  that  metaphysics  consists  altogether  of  such 
connexions.  I  sought  to  ascertain  their  number,  and 
when  I  had  satisfactorily  succeeded  in  this  by  starting 
from  a  single  principle,  I  proceeded  to  the  deduction 
of  these  concepts,  which  I  was  now  certain  were  not 
deduced  from  experience,  as  Hume  had  apprehended, 
but  sprang  from  the  pure  understanding.  This  de 
duction  (which  seemed  impossible  to  my  acute  prede 
cessor,  which  had  never  even  occurred  to  any  one 


8  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

else,  though  no  one  had  hesitated  to  use  the  concepts 
without  investigating  the  basis  of  their  objective  val 
idity)  was  the  most  difficult  task  ever  undertaken  in  the 
service  of  metaphysics ;  and  the  worst  was  that  meta 
physics,  such  as  it  then  existed,  could  not  assist  me 
in  the  least,  because  this  deduction  alone  can  render 
metaphysics  possible.  But  as  soon  as  I  had  succeeded 
in  solving  Hume's  problem  not  merely  in  a  particular 
case,  but  with  respect  to  the  whole  faculty  of  pure  rea 
son,  I  could  proceed  safely,  though  slowly,  to  determine 
the  whole  sphere  of  pure  reason  completely  and  from 
general  principles,  in  its  circumference  as  well  as  in  its 
contents.  This  was  required  for  metaphysics  in  order  to 
construct  its  system  according  to  a  reliable  method. 

But  I  fear  that  the  execution  of  Hume's  problem 
in  its  widest  extent  (viz.,  my  Critique  of  the  Pure  Rea 
son)  will  fare  as  the  problem  itself  fared,  when  first 
proposed.  It  will  be  misjudged  because  it  is  mis 
understood,  and  misunderstood  because  men  choose 
to  skim  through  the  book,  and  not  to  think  through 
it — a  disagreeable  task,  because  the  work  is  dry,  ob 
scure,  opposed  to  all  ordinary  notions,  and  moreover 
long-winded.  I  confess,  however,  I  did  not  expect  to 
hear  from  philosophers  complaints  of  want  of  popu 
larity,  entertainment,  and  facility,  when  the  existence 
of  a  highly  prized  and  indispensable  cognition  is  at 
stake,  which  cannot  be  established  otherwise,  than  by 
the  strictest  rules  of  methodic  precision.  Popularity 
may  follow,  but  is  inadmissible  at  the  beginning.  Yet 
as  regards  a  certain  obscurity,  arising  partly  from  the 
diffuseness  of  the  plan,  owing  to  which  the  principal 
points  of  the  investigation  are  easily  lost  sight  of,  the 


INTRODUCTION.  9 

complaint  is  just,  and  I  intend  to  remove  it  by  the 
present  Prolegomena. 

The  first-mentioned  work,  which  discusses  the  pure 
faculty  of  reason  in  its  whole  compass  and  bounds, 
will  remain  the  foundation,  to  which  the  Prolegomena, 
as  a  preliminary  exercise,  refer;  for  our  critique  must 
first  be  established  as  a  complete  and  perfected  sci 
ence,  before  we  can  think  of  letting  Metaphysics  ap 
pear  on  the  scene,  or  even  have  the  most  distant  hope 
of  attaining  it. 

We  have  been  long  accustomed  to  seeing  anti 
quated  knowledge  produced  as  new  by  taking  it  out 
of  its  former  context,  and  reducing  it  to  system  in  a 
new  suit  of  any  fancy  pattern  under  new  titles.  Most 
readers  will  set  out  by  expecting  nothing  else  from 
the  Critique;  but  these  Prolegomena  may  persuade 
him  that  it  is  a  perfectly  new  science,  of  which  no 
one  has  ever  even  thought,  the  very  idea  of  which 
was  unknown,  and  for  which  nothing  hitherto  accom 
plished  can  be  of  the  smallest  use,  except  it  be  the 
suggestion  of  Hume's  doubts.  Yet  even  he  did  not 
suspect  such  a  formal  science,  but  ran  his  ship  ashore, 
for  safety's  sake,  landing  on  scepticism,  there  to  let  it 
lie  and  rot ;  whereas  my  object  is  rather  to  give  it  a 
pilot,  who,  by  means  of  safe  astronomical  principles 
drawn  from  a  knowledge  of  the  globe,  and  provided 
with  a  complete  chart  and  compass,  may  steer  the 
ship  safely,  whither  he  listeth. 

If  in  a  new  science,  which  is  wholly  isolated  and 
unique  in  its  kind,  we  started  with  the  prejudice  that 
we  can  judge  of  things  by  means  of  our  previously 
acquired  knowledge,  which  is  precisely  what  has  first 
to  be  called  in  question,  we  should  only  fancy  we  saw 
everywhere  what  we  had  already  known,  the  expres- 


io  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

sions,  having  a  similar  sound,  only  that  all  would  ap 
pear  utterly  metamorphosed,  senseless  and  unintelli 
gible,  because  we  should  have  as  a  foundation  our 
own  notions,  made  by  long  habit  a  second  nature,  in 
stead  of  the  author's.  But  the  longwindedness  of  the 
work,  so  far  as  it  depends  on  the  subject,  and  not  the 
exposition,  its  consequent  unavoidable  dryness  and 
its  scholastic  precision  are  qualities  which  can  only 
benefit  the  science,  though  they  may  discredit  the 
book. 

Few  writers  are  gifted  with  the  subtilty,  and  at  the 
same  time  with  the  grace,  of  David  Hume,  or  with 
the  depth,  as  well  as  the  elegance,  of  Moses  Mendels 
sohn.  Yet  I  flatter  myself  I  might  have  made  my 
own  exposition  popular,  had  my  object  been  merely  to 
sketch  out  a  plan  and  leave  its  completion  to  others, 
instead  of  having  my  heart  in  the  welfare  of  the  sci 
ence,  to  which  I  had  devoted  myself  so  long  ;  in  truth, 
it  required  no  little  constancy,  and  even  self-denial, 
to  postpone  the  sweets  of  an  immediate  success  to 
the  prospect  of  a  slower,  but  more  lasting,  reputation. 

Making  plans  is  often  the  occupation  of  an  opu 
lent  and  boastful  mind,  which  thus  obtains  the  repu 
tation  of  a  creative  genius,  by  demanding  what  it 
cannot  itself  supply;  by  censuring,  what  it  cannot 
improve ;  and  by  proposing,  what  it  knows  not  where 
to  find.  And  yet  something  more  should  belong  to  a 
sound  plan  of  a  general  critique  of  pure  reason  than 
mere  conjectures,  if  this  plan  is  to  be  other  than  the 
usual  declamations  of  pious  aspirations.  But  pure 
reason  is  a  sphere  so  separate  and  self-contained,  that 
we  cannot  touch  a  part  without  affecting  all  the  rest. 
We  can  therefore  do  nothing  without  first  determin 
ing  the  position  of  each  part,  and  its  relation  to  the 


INTRODUCTION.  X I 

rest;  for,  as  our  judgment  cannot  be  corrected  by 
anything  without,  the  validity  and  use  of  every  part 
depends  upon  the  relation  in  which  it  stands  to  all 
the  rest  within  the  domain  of  reason. 

So  in  the  structure  of  an  organized  body,  the  end 
of  each  member  can  only  be  deduced  from  the  full 
conception  of  the  whole.  It  may,  then,  be  said  of 
such  a  critique  that  it  is  never  trustworthy  except  it 
be  perfectly  complete,  down  to  the  smallest  elements 
of  pure  reason.  In  the  sphere  of  this  faculty  you  can 
determine  either  everything  or  nothing. 

But  although  a  mere  sketch,  preceding  the  Critique 
of  Pure  Reason,  would  be  unintelligible,  unreliable, 
and  useless,  it  is  all  the  more  useful  as  a  sequel.  For 
so  we  are  able  to  grasp  the  whole,  to  examine  in  de 
tail  the  chief  points  of  importance  in  the  science,  and 
to  improve  in  many  respects  our  exposition,  as  com 
pared  with  the  first  execution  of  the  work. 

After  the  completion  of  the  work  I  offer  here  such 
a  plan  which  is  sketched  out  after  an  analytical 
method,  while  the  work  itself  had  to  be  executed  in 
the  synthetical  style,  in  order  that  the  science  may 
present  all  its  articulations,  as  the  structure  of  a  pe 
culiar  cognitive  faculty,  in  their  natural  combination. 
But  should  any  reader  find  this  plan,  which  I  publish 
as  the  Prolegomena  to  any  future  Metaphysics,  still 
obscure,  let  him  consider  that  not  every  one  is  bound 
to  study  Metaphysics,  that  many  minds  will  succeed 
very  well,  in  the  exact  and  even  in  deep  sciences, 
more  closely  allied  to  practical  experience,1  while  they 

IThe  term  Anschauung  here  used  means  sense-perception.  It  is  that 
which  is  given  to  the  senses  and  apprehended  immediately,  as  an  object  is 
seen  by  merely  looking  at  it.  The  translation  intuition,  though  etymolog- 
ically  correct,  is  misleading.  In  the  present  passage  the  term  is  not  used  in 
its  technical  significance  but  means  "  practical  experience." — Ed. 


1 2  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

cannot  succeed  in  investigations  dealing  exclusively 
with  abstract  concepts.  In  such  cases  men  should 
apply  their  talents  to  other  subjects.  But  he  who 
undertakes  to  judge,  or  still  more,  to  construct,  a  sys 
tem  of  Metaphysics,  must  satisfy  the  demands  here 
made,  either  by  adopting  my  solution,  or  by  thor 
oughly  refuting  it,  and  substituting  another.  To 
evade  it  is  impossible. 

In  conclusion,  let  it  be  remembered  that  this 
much-abused  obscurity  (frequently  serving  as  a  mere 
pretext  under  which  people  hide  their  own  indolence 
or  dullness)  has  its  uses,  since  all  who  in  other  sci 
ences  observe  a  judicious  silence,  speak  authorita 
tively  in  metaphysics  and  make  bold  decisions,  be 
cause  their  ignorance  is  not  here  contrasted  with  the 
knowledge  of  others.  Yet  it  does  contrast  with  sound 
critical  principles,  which  we  may  therefore  commend 
in  the  words  of  Virgil : 

"Ignavum,  fucos,  pecus  a  prsesepibus  arcent." 
'Bees  are  defending  their  hives  against  drones,  those  indolent 
creatures." 


PROLEGOMENA. 


PREAMBLE  ON  THE   PECULIARITIES    OF  ALL   META 
PHYSICAL  COGNITION. 

§  i .    Of  the  Sources  of  Metaphysics* 

IF  it  becomes  desirable  to  formulate  any  cognition 
as  science,  it  will  be  necessary  first  to  determine 
accurately  those  peculiar  features  which  no  other  sci' 
ence  has  in  common  with  it,  constituting  its  charac 
teristics  ;  otherwise  the  boundaries  of  all  sciences 
become  confused,  and  none  of  them  can  be  treated 
thoroughly  according  to  its  nature. 

The  characteristics  of  a  science  may  consist  of  a 
simple  difference  of  object,  or  of  the  sources  of  cogni 
tion,  or  of  the  kind  of  cognition,  or  perhaps  of  all 
three  conjointly.  On  this,  therefore,  depends  the 
idea  of  a  possible  science  and  its  territory. 

First,  as  concerns  the  sources  of  metaphysical 
cognition,  its  very  concept  implies  that  they  cannot 
be  empirical.  Its  principles  (including  not  only  its 
maxims  but  its  basic  notions)  must  never  be  derived 
from  experience.  It  must  not  be  physical  but  meta 
physical  knowledge,  viz.,  knowledge  lying  beyond 
experience.  It  can  therefore  have  for  its  basis  neither 
external  experience,  which  is  the  source  of  physics 
proper,  nor  internal,  which  is  the  basis  of  empirical 


14  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

psychology.     It  is  therefore  a  priori  knowledge,  com 
ing  from  pure  Understanding  and  pure  Reason. 

But  so  far  Metaphysics  would  not  be  distinguish 
able  from  pure  Mathematics;  it  must  therefore  be 
called  pure  philosophical  cognition ;  and  for  the 
meaning  of  this  term  I  refer  to  the  Critique  of  the 
Pure  Reason  (II.  "Method  of  Transcendentalism," 
Chap.  I.,  Sec.  i),  where  the  distinction  between  these 
two  employments  of  the  reason  is  sufficiently  ex 
plained.  So  far  concerning  the  sources  of  metaphysi 
cal  cognition. 

§  2.    Concerning  the  Kind  of  Cognition  which  can  alone 
be  called  Metaphysical. 

a.  Of  the  Distinction  between  Analytical  and  Syn 
thetical  Judgments  in  general. — The  peculiarity  of  its 
sources  demands  that  metaphysical  cognition  must 
consist  of  nothing  but  a  priori  judgments.  But  what 
ever  be  their  origin,  or  their  logical  form,  there  is  a 
distinction  in  judgments,  as  to  their  content,  accord 
ing  to  which  they  are  either  merely  explicative,  add 
ing  nothing  to  the  content  of  the  cognition,  or  expan 
sive,  increasing  the  given  cognition :  the  former  may 
be  called  analytical,  the  latter  synthetical,  judgments. 

Analytical  judgments  express  nothing  in  the  predi 
cate  but  what  has  been  already  actually  thought  in 
the  concept  of  the  subject,  though  not  so  distinctly  or 
vrith  the  same  (full)  consciousness.  When  I  say:  All 
bodies  are  extended,  I  have  not  amplified  in  the  least 
my  concept  of  body,  but  have  only  analysed  it,  as  ex 
tension  was  really  thought  to  belong  to  that  concept 
before  the  judgment  was  made,  though  it  was  not  ex 
pressed  ?  this  judgment  is  therefore  analytical.  On 
the  contrary,  this  judgment,  All  bodies  have  weight, 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  15 

contains  in  its  predicate  something  not  actually 
thought  in  the  general  concept  of  the  body;  it  ampli 
fies  my  knowledge  by  adding  something  to  my  con 
cept,  and  must  therefore  be  called  synthetical. 

b.  The  Common  Principle  of  all  Analytical  Judgments 
is  the  Law  of  Contradiction. — All  analytical  judgments 
depend  wholly  on  the  law  of  Contradiction,  and  are 
in  their  nature  a  priori  cognitions,  whether  the  con 
cepts  that  supply  them  with  matter  be  empirical  or 
not.     For  the  predicate  of  an  affirmative  analytical 
judgment  is  already  contained  in  the  concept  of  the 
subject,  of  which  it  cannot  be  denied  without  contra 
diction.     In  the  same  way  its  opposite  is  necessarily 
denied  of  the  subject  in  an  analytical,  but  negative, 
judgment,  by  the  same  law  of  contradiction.     Such  is 
the  nature  of  the  judgments  :  all  bodies  are  extended, 
and  no  bodies  are  unextended  (i.  e.,  simple). 

For  this  very  reason  all  analytical  judgments  are 
a  priori  even  when  the  concepts  are  empirical,  as,  for 
example,  Gold  is  a  yellow  metal ;  for  to  know  this  I 
require  110  experience  beyond  my  concept  of  gold  as 
a  yellow  metal :  it  is,  in  fact,  the  very  concept,  and  I 
need  only  analyse  it,  without  looking  beyond  it  else 
where. 

c.  Synthetical  Judgments  require  a  different  Principle 
from  the  Law  of  Contradiction. — There  are  synthetical 
a  posteriori  judgments  of  empirical  origin;  but  there 
are  also  others  which  are  proved  to  be  certain  a  priori, 
and  which  spring  from  pure  Understanding  and  Rea 
son.     Yet  they  both  agree  in  this,  that  they  cannot 
possibly  spring  from  the  principle  of  analysis,  viz., 
the  law  of  contradiction,  alone ;  they  require  a  quite 
different  principle,  though,  from  whatever  they  may 
be  deduced,  they  must  be  subject  to  the  law  of  con- 


i6  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

tradiction,  which  must  never  be  violated,  even  though 
everything  cannot  be  deduced  from  it.  I  shall  first 
classify  synthetical  judgments. 

1.  Empirical  Judgments  are  always  synthetical.   For 
it  would  be  absurd  to  base  an  analytical  judgment  on 
experience,   as  our  concept  suffices  tor  the  purpose 
without    requiring   any   testimony   from    experience. 
That  body  is  extended,  is  a  judgment  established  a 
priori,  and  not  an  empirical  judgment.      For  before 
appealing  to  experience,  we  already  have  all  the  con 
ditions  of  the  judgment  in  the  concept,  from  which 
we  have  but  to  elicit  the  predicate  according  to  the 
law  of  contradiction,  and  thereby  to  become  conscious 
of  the  necessity  of  the  judgment,  which  experience 
could  not  even  teach  us. 

2.  Mathematical  Judgments  are  all  synthetical.   This 
fact   seems   hitherto  to   have  altogether  escaped  the 
observation  of  those  who  have  analysed  human  rea 
son  ;  it  even  seems  directly  opposed  to  all  their  con 
jectures,  though  incontestably  certain,  and  most  im 
portant  in  its  consequences.    For  as  it  was  found  that 
the  conclusions  of  mathematicians  all  proceed  accord 
ing  to  the  law  of  contradiction  (as  is  demanded  by  all 
apodeictic  certainty),  men  persuaded  themselves  that 
the  fundamental  principles  were  known  from  the  same 
law.   This  was  a  great  mistake,  for  a  synthetical  prop 
osition  can  indeed  be  comprehended  according  to  the 
law  of  contradiction,  but  only  by  presupposing  another 
synthetical    proposition    from    wnich    it  follows,   but 
never  in  itself. 

First  of  all,  we  must  observe  that  all  proper  math 
ematical  judgments  are  a  priori,  and  not  empirical, 
because  they  carry  with  them  necessity,  which  cannot 
be  obtained  from  experience.  But  if  this  be  not  con- 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  17 

ceded  to  me,  very  good ;  I  shall  confine  my  assertion 
to  pure  Mathematics,  the  very  notion  of  which  implies 
that  it  contains  pure  a  priori  and  not  empirical  cogni 
tions. 

It  might  at  first  be  thought  that  the  proposition 
7-j-5  =  i2  is  a  mere  analytical  judgment,  following 
from  the  concept  of  the  sum  of  seven  and  five,  accord 
ing  to  the  law  of  contradiction.  But  on  closer  exam 
ination  it  appears  that  the  concept  of  the  sum  of  7+5 
contains  merely  their  union  in  a  single  number,  with 
out  its  being  at  all  thought  what  the  particular  num 
ber  is  that  unites  them.  The  concept  of  twelve  is  by 
no  means  thought  by  merely  thinking  of  the  combina 
tion  of  seven  and  five ;  and  analyse  this  possible  sum 
as  we  may,  we  shall  not  discover  twelve  in  the  con 
cept.  We  must  go  beyond  these  concepts,  by  calling  to 
our  aid  some  concrete  image  (Anschauun^),  i.e.,  either 
our  five  fingers,  or  five  points  (as  Segner  has  it  in  his 
Arithmetic),  and  we  must  add  successively  the  units 
of  the  five,  given  in  some  concrete  image  {Anschau- 
ung),  to  the  concept  of  seven.  Hence  our  concept 
is  really  amplified  by  the  proposition  7-^5  =  12,  and 
we  add  to  the  first  a  second,  not  thought  in  it.  Arith 
metical  judgments  are  therefore  synthetical,  and  the 
more  plainly  according  as  we  take  larger  numbers; 
for  in  such  cases  it  is  clear  that,  however  closely  we 
analyse  our  concepts  without  calling  visual  images 
{Anschauung}  to  our  aid,  we  can  never  find  the  sum  by 
such  mere  dissection. 

All  principles  of  geometry  are  no  less  analytical. 
That  a  straight  line  is  the  shortest  path  between  two 
points,  is  a  synthetical  proposition.  For  my  concept 
of  straight  contains  nothing  of  quantity,  but  only  a 
quality.  The  attribute  of  shortness  is  therefore  alto- 


18  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

gether  additional,  and  cannot  be  obtained  by  any 
analysis  of  the  concept.  Here,  too,  visualisation 
(Anschauung}  must  come  to  aid  us.  It  alone  makes 
the  synthesis  possible. 

Some  other  principles,  assumed  by  geometers,  are 
indeed  actually  analytical,  and  depend  on  the  law  of 
contradiction ;  but  they  only  serve,  as  identical  prop 
ositions,  as  a  method  of  concatenation,  and  not  as 
principles,  e.  g.,  a  =  a,  the  whole  is  equal  to  itself,  or 
a-\-b*>(ij  the  whole  is  greater  than  its  part.  And  yet 
even  these,  though  they  are  recognised  as  valid  from 
mere  concepts,  are  only  admitted  in  mathematics,  be 
cause  they  can  be  represented  in  some  visual  form 
{Anschauung}.  What  usually  makes  us  believe  that 
the  predicate  of  such  apodeictic1  judgments  is  already 
contained  in  our  concept,  and  that  the  judgment  is 
therefore  analytical,  is  the  duplicity  of  the  expression, 
requesting  us  to  think  a  certain  predicate  as  of  neces 
sity  implied  in  the  thought  of  a  given  concept,  which 
necessity  attaches  to  the  concept.  But  the  question 
is  not  what  we  are  requested  to  join  in  thought  to  the 
given  concept,  but  what  we  actually  think  together 
with  and  in  it,  though  obscurely ;  and  so  it  appears 
that  the  predicate  belongs  to  these  concepts  necessa 
rily  indeed,  yet  not  directly  but  indirectly  by  an  added 
visualisation  (Anschauung). 

§  3.    A  Remark  on  the   General  Division  of  Judgments 

into  Analytical  and  Synthetical. 

This  division  is  indispensable,  as  concerns  the 
Critique  of  human  understanding,  and  therefore  de- 

IThe  term  apodeictic  is  borrowed  by  Kant  from  Aristotle  who  uses  it  in 
the  sense  of  "certain  beyond  dispute."  The  word  is  derived  from  airo&eCKWfju 
(WjAow)and  is  contrasted  to  dialectic  propositions,  i.  e.,  such  statements 
as  admit  of  controversy.— Ed, 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  IQ 

serves  to  be  called  classical,  though  otherwise  it  is  of 
little  use,  but  this  is  the  reason  why  dogmatic  philos 
ophers,  who  always  seek  the  sources  of  metaphysical 
judgments  in  Metaphysics  itself,  and  not  apart  from 
it,  in  the  pure  laws  of  reason  generally,  altogether 
neglected  this  apparently  obvious  distinction.  Thus 
the  celebrated  Wolf,  and  his  acute  follower  Baum- 
garten,  came  to  seek  the  proof  of  the  principle  of 
Sufficient  Reason,  which  is  clearly  synthetical,  in  the 
principle  of  Contradiction.  In  Locke's  Essay,  how 
ever,  I  find  an  indication  of  my  division.  For  in  the 
fourth  book  (chap.  iii.  §  9,  seq.),  having  discussed 
the  various  connexions  of  representations  in  judg 
ments,  and  their  sources,  one  of  which  he  makes 
" identity  and  contradiction"  (analytical  judgments), 
and  another  the  coexistence  of  representations  in  a 
subject,  he  confesses  (§  10)  that  our  a  priori  knowl 
edge  of  the  latter  is  very  narrow,  and  almost  nothing. 
But  in  his  remarks  on  this  species  of  cognition,  there 
is  so  little  of  what  is  definite,  and  reduced  to  rules, 
that  we  cannot  wonder  if  no  one,  not  even  Hume,  was 
led  to  make  investigations  concerning  this  sort  of 
judgments.  For  such  general  and  yet  definite  prin 
ciples  are  not  easily  learned  from  other  men,  who 
have  had  them  obscurely  in  their  minds.  We  must 
hit  on  them  first  by  our  own  reflexion,  then  we  find 
them  elsewhere,  where  we  could  not  possibly  nave 
found  them  at  first,  because  the  authors  themselves 
did  not  know  that  such  an  idea  lay  at  the  basis  of 
their  observations.  Men  who  never  think  indepen 
dently  have  nevertheless  the  acuteness  to  discover 
everything,  after  it  has  been  once  shown  them,  in 
what  was  said  long  since,  though  no  one  ever  saw  it 
there  before. 


KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


§  4.    The  General  Question  of  the  Prolegomena. — 2s 
Metaphysics  at  all  Possible  ?  * 

Were  a  metaphysics,  which  could  maintain  its 
place  as  a  science,  really  in  existence ;  could  we  say, 
here  is  metaphysics,  learn  it,  and  it  will  convince  you 
irresistibly  and  irrevocably  of  its  truth  :  this  question 
would  be  useless,  and  there  would  only  remain  that 
other  question  (which  would  rather  be  a  test  of  our 
acuteness,  than  a  proof  of  the  existence  of  the  thing 
itself),  "How  is  the  science  possible,  and  how  does 
reason  come  to  attain  it?"  But  human  reason  has 
not  been  so  fortunate  in  this  case.  There  is  no  single 
book  to  which  you  can  point  as  you  do  to  Euclid,  and 
say:  This  is  Metaphysics;  here  you  may  find  the 
noblest  objects  of  this  science,  the  knowledge  of  a 
highest  Being,  and  of  a  future  existence,  proved  from 
principles  of  pure  reason.  We  can  be  shown  indeed 
many  judgments,  demonstrably  certain,  and  never 
questioned ;  but  these  are  all  analytical,  and  rather 
concern  the  materials  and  the  scaffolding  for  Meta 
physics,  than  the  extension  of  knowledge,  which  i? 
our  proper  object  in  studying  it  (§  2).  Even  suppo 
sing  you  produce  synthetical  judgments  (such  as  the 
law  of  Sufficient  Reason,  which  you  have  never 
proved,  as  you  ought  to,  from  pure  reason  a  priori, 
though  we  gladly  concede  its  truth),  you  lapse  when 
they  come  to  be  employed  for  your  principal  object, 
into  such  doubtful  assertions,  that  in  all  ages  one 
Metaphysics  has  contradicted  another,  either  in  its 
assertions,  or  their  proofs,  and  thus  has  itself  des 
troyed  its  own  claim  to  lasting  assent.  Nay,  the  very 
attempts  to  set  up  such  a  science  are  the  main  cause 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  22 

of  the  early  appearance  of  scepticism,  a  mental  atti 
tude  in  which  reason  treats  itself  with  such  violence 
that  it  could  never  have  arisen  save  from  complete 
despair  of  ever  satisfying  our  most  important  aspira 
tions.  For  long  before  men  began  to  inquire  into  na 
ture  methodically,  they  consulted  abstract  reason, 
which  had  to  some  extent  been  exercised  by  means  of 
ordinary  experience;  for  reason  is  ever  present,  while 
laws  of  nature  must  usually  be  discovered  with  labor. 
So  Metaphysics  floated  to  the  surface,  like  foam,  which 
dissolved  the  moment  it  was  scooped  off.  But  imme 
diately  there  appeared  a  new  supply  on  the  surface, 
to  be  ever  eagerly  gathered  up  by  some,  while  others, 
instead  of  seeking  in  the  depths  the  cause  of  the  phe 
nomenon,  thought  they  showed  their  wisdom  by  ridi 
culing  the  idle  labor  of  their  neighbors. 

The  essential  and  distinguishing  feature  of  pure 
mathematical  cognition  among  all  other  a  priori  cog 
nitions  is,  that  it  cannot  at  all  proceed  from  concepts, 
but  only  by  means  of  the  construction  of  concepts 
(see  Critique  II.,  Method  of  Transcendentalism, 
chap.  I.,  sect.  i).  As  therefore  in  its  judgments  it 
must  proceed  beyond  the  concept  to  that  which  its 
corresponding  visualisation  (Anschauung}  contains, 
these  judgments  neither  can,  nor  ought  to,  arise  ana 
lytically,  by  dissecting  the  concept,  but  are  all  syn 
thetical. 

I  cannot  refrain  from  pointing  out  the  disadvan 
tage  resulting  to  philosophy  from  the  neglect  of  this 
easy  and  apparently  insignificant  observation.  Hume 
being  prompted  (a  task  worthy  of  a  philosopher)  to 
cast  his  eye  over  the  whole  field  of  a  priori  cognitions 
in  which  human  understanding  claims  such  mighty 
possessions,  heedlessly  severed  from  it  a  whole,  and 


22  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

indeed  its  most  valuable,  province,  viz.,  pure  mathe 
matics;  for  he  thought  its  nature,  or,  so  to  speak, 
the  state-constitution  of  this  empire,  depended  on 
totally  different  principles,  namely,  on  the  law  of 
contradiction  alone;  and  although  he  did  not  divide 
judgments  in  this  manner  formally  and  universally  as 
I  have  done  here,  what  he  said  was  equivalent  to  this: 
that  mathematics  contains  only  analytical,  but  meta 
physics  synthetical,  a  priori  judgments.  In  this,  how 
ever,  he  was  greatly  mistaken,  and  the  mistake  had  a 
decidedly  injurious  effect  upon  his  whole  conception. 
But  for  this,  he  would  have  extended  his  question 
concerning  the  origin  of  our  synthetical  judgments 
far  beyond  the  metaphysical  concept  of  Causality, 
and  included  in  it  the  possibility  of  mathematics  a 
priori  also,  for  this  latter  he  must  have  assumed  to 
be  equally  synthetical.  And  then  he  could  not  have 
based  his  metaphysical  judgments  on  mere  experience 
without  subjecting  the  axioms  of  mathematics  equally 
to  experience,  a  thing  which  he  was  far  too  acute  to 
do.  The  good  company  into  which  metaphysics  would 
thus  have  been  brought,  would  have  saved  it  from 
the  danger  of  a  contemptuous  ill-treatment,  for  the 
thrust  intended  for  it  must  have  reached  mathematics, 
which  was  not  and  could  not  have  been  Hume's  in 
tention.  Thus  that  acute  man  would  have  been  led 
into  considerations  which  must  needs  be  similar  to 
those  that  now  occupy  us,  but  which  would  have 
gained  inestimably  >  v  his  inimitably  elegant  style. 

Metaphysical  judgments,  properly  so  called,  are  all 
synthetical.  We  must  distinguish  judgments  pertain 
ing  to  metaphysics  from  metaphysical  judgments 
properly  so  called.  Many  of  the  former  are  analytical, 
but  they  only  afford  the  means  for  metaphysical  judg- 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  23 

ments,  which  are  the  whole  end  of  the  science,  and 
which  are  always  synthetical.  For  if  there  be  con 
cepts  pertaining  to  metaphysics  (as,  for  example,  that 
of  substance),  the  judgments  springing  from  simple 
analysis  of  them  also  pertain  to  metaphysics,  as,  for 
example,  substance  is  that  which  only  exists  as  sub 
ject;  and  by  means  of  several  such  analytical  judg 
ments,  we  seek  to  approach  the  definition  of  the  con 
cept.  But  as  the  analysis  of  a  pure  concept  of  the 
understanding  pertaining  to  metaphysics,  does  not 
proceed  in  any  different  manner  from  the  dissection 
of  any  other,  even  empirical,  concepts,  not  pertaining 
to  metaphysics  (such  as :  air  is  an  elastic  fluid,  the 
elasticity  of  which  is  not  destroyed  by  any  known  de 
gree  of  cold),  it  follows  that  the  concept  indeed,  but 
not  the  analytical  judgment,  is  properly  metaphysical. 
This  science  has  something  peculiar  in  the  production 
of  its  a  priori  cognitions,  which  must  therefore  be  dis 
tinguished  from  the  features  it  has  in  common  with 
other  rational  knowledge.  Thus  the  judgment,  that 
all  the  substance  in  things  is  permanent,  is  a  synthet 
ical  and  properly  metaphysical  judgment. 

If  the  a  priori  principles,  which  constitute  the  ma 
terials  of  metaphysics,  have  first  been  collected  ac 
cording  to  fixed  principles,  then  their  analysis  will  be 
of  great  value ;  it  might  be  taught  as  a  particular  part 
(as  a  philosophia  definitive?),  containing  nothing  but 
analytical  judgments  pertaining  to  metaphysics,  and 
could  be  treated  separately  from  the  synthetical  which 
constitute  metaphysics  proper.  For  indeed  these 
analyses  are  not  elsewhere  of  much  value,  except  in 
metaphysics,  i.  e.,  as  regards  the  synthetical  judg 
ments,  which  are  to  be  generated  by  these  previously 
analysed  concepts. 


24  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

The  conclusion  drawn  in  this  section  then  is,  that 
metaphysics  is  properly  concerned  with  synthetical 
propositions  a  priori,  and  these  alone  constitute  its 
end,  for  which  it  indeed  requires  various  dissections 
of  its  concepts,  viz.,  of  its  analytical  judgments,  but 
wherein  the  procedure  is  not  different  from  that  in 
every  other  kind  of  knowledge,  in  wlpch  we  merely 
seek  to  render  our  concepts  distinct  by  analysis,  But 
the  generation  of  a  priori  cognition  by  concrete  im 
ages  as  well  as  by  concepts,  in  fine  of  synthetical 
propositions  a  priori  in  philosophical  cognition,  con 
stitutes  the  essential  subject  of  Metaphysics. 

Weary  therefore  as  well  of  dogmatism,  which 
teaches  us  nothing,  as  of  scepticism,  which  does  not 
even  promise  us  anything,  not  even  the  quiet  state  of 
a  contented  ignorance;  disquieted  by  the  importance 
of  knowledge  so  much  needed;  and  lastly,  rendered 
suspicious  by  long  experience  of  all  knowledge  which 
we  believe  we  possess,  or  which  offers  itself,  under  the 
title  of  pure  reason :  there  remains  but  one  critical 
question  on  the  answer  to  which  our  future  procedure 
depends,  viz.,  Is  Metaphysics  at  all  possible?  But  this 
question  must  be  answered  not  by  sceptical  objections 
to  the  asseverations  of  some  actual  system  of  meta 
physics  (for  we  do  not  as  yet  admit  such  a  thing  to 
exist),  but  from  the  conception,  as  yet  only  proble 
matical,  of  a  science  of  this  sort. 

In  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  I  have  treated  this 
question  synthetically,  by  making  inquiries  into  pure 
reason  itself,  and  endeavoring  in  this  source  to  deter 
mine  the  elements  as  well  as  the  laws  of  its  pure  use 
according  to  principles.  The  task  is  difficult,  and 
requires  a  resolute  reader  to  penetrate  by  degrees  into 
a  system,  based  on  no  data  except  reason  itself,  and 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  25 

which  therefore  seeks,  without  resting  upon  any  fact, 
to  unfold  knowledge  from  its  original  germs.  Prole 
gomena,  however,  are  designed  for  preparatory  exer 
cises;  they  are  intended  rather  to  point  out  what  \ve 
have  to  do  in  order  if  possible  to  actualise  a  science, 
than  to  propound  it.  They  must  therefore  rest  upon 
something  already  known  as  trustworthy,  from  which 
we  can  set  out  with  confidence,  and  ascend  to  sources 
as  yet  unknown,  the  discovery  of  which  will  not  only 
explain  to  us  what  we  knew,  but  exhibit  a  sphere  of 
many  cognitions  which  all  spring  from  the  same 
sources.  The  method  of  Prolegomena,  especially  of 
those  designed  as  a  preparation  for  future  metaphys 
ics,  is  consequently  analytical. 

But  it  happens  fortunately,  that  though  we  cannot 
assume  metaphysics  to  be  an  actual  science,  we  can  say 
with  confidence  that  certain  pure  a  priori  synthetical 
cognitions,  pure  Mathematics  and  pure  Physics  are 
actual  and  given  ;  for  both  contain  propositions,  which 
are  thoroughly  recognised  as  apodeictically  certain, 
partly  by  mere  reason,  partly  by  general  consent  aris 
ing  from  experience,  and  yet  as  independent  of  expe 
rience.  We  have  therefore  some  at  least  uncontested 
synthetical  knowledge  a  priori,  and  need  not  ask 
whether  it  be  possible,  for  it  is  actual,  but  how  it  is 
possible,  in  order  that  we  may  deduce  from  the  prin 
ciple  which  makes  the  given  cognitions  possible  the 
possibility  of  all  the  rest. 

The  General  Problem:  How  is  Cognition  from  Pure 

Reason  Possible? 

§  5.  We  have  above  learned  the  significant  dis 
tinction  between  analytical  and  synthetical  judgments. 
The  possibility  of  analytical  propositions  was  easily 


26  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

comprehended,  being  entirely  founded  on  the  law  ot 
Contradiction.  The  possibility  of  synthetical  a  pos 
ter  wri  judgments,  of  those  which  are  gathered  horn 
experience,  also  requires  no  particular  explanation  ; 
for  experience  is  nothing  but  a  continual  synthesis  of 
perceptions.  There  remain  therefore  only  synthetical 
propositions  a  priori,  of  which  the  possibility  must 
be  sought  or  investigated,  because  they  must  depend 
upon  other  principles  than  the  law  of  contradiction. 

But  here  we  need  not  first  establish  the  possibility 
of  such  propositions  so  as  to  ask  whether  they  are 
possible.  For  there  are  enough  of  them  which  indeed 
are  of  undoubted  certainty,  and  as  our  present  method 
is  analytical,  we  shall  start  from  the  fact,  that  such 
synthetical  but  purely  rational  cognition  actually  ex 
ists  ;  but  we  must  now  inquire  into  the  reason  of  this 
possibility,  and  ask,  how  such  cognition  is  possible, 
in  order  that  we  may  from  the  principles  of  its  possi 
bility  be  enabled  to  determine  the  conditions  of  its 
use,  its  sphere  and  its  limits.  The  proper  problem 
upon  which  all  depends,  when  expressed  with  scho 
lastic  precision,  is  therefore : 

How  are  Synthetic  Propositions  a  priori  possible? 

.b'or  the  sake  of  popularity^  have  above  expressed 
this  problem  somewhat  differently,  as  an  inquiry  into 
purely  rational  cognition,  which  I  could  do  for  once 
without  detriment  to  the  desired  comprehension,  be 
cause,  as  we  have  only  to  do  here  with  metaphysics 
and  its  sources,  the  reader  will,  I  hope,  after  the  fore 
going  remarks,  keep  in  mind  that  when  we  speak  of 
purely  rational  cognition,  we  do  not  mean  analytical, 
but  synthetical  cognition.1 

1  It  is  unavoidable  that  as  knowledge  advances,  certain  expressions  which 
have  become  classical,  after  having  been  used  since  the  infancy  of  science, 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  27 

Metaphysics  stands  or  falls  with  the  solution  of 
this  problem :  its  very  existence  depends  upon  it. 
Let  any  one  make  metaphysical  assertions  with  ever 
so  much  plausibility,  let  him  overwhelm  us  with  con 
clusions,  if  he  has  not  previously  proved  able  to  an 
swer  this  question  satisfactorily,  I  have  a  right  to  say: 
this  is  all  vain  baseless  philosophy  and  false  wisdom. 
You  speak  through  pure  reason,  and  claim,  as  it  were 
to  create  cognitions  a  priori  by  not  only  dissecting 
given  concepts,  but  also  by  asserting  connexions  which 
do  not  rest  upon  the  law  of  contradiction,  and  which 
you  believe  you  conceive  quite  independently  of  all  ex 
perience  ;  how  do  you  arrive  at  this,  and  how  will 
you  justify  your  pretensions?  An  appeal  to  the  con 
sent  of  the  Qojnmaa.  sense  of  mankind  cannot  be 
allowed;  for  that  is  a  witness  whose  authority  de 
pends  merely  upon  rumor.  Says  Horace: 

"  Quodcunque  ostendis  mihi  sic,  incredulus  odi." 
"  To  all  that  which  thou  provest  me  thus,  I  refuse  to  give 
credence." 

The  answer  to  this  question,  though  indispensable, 
is  difficult;  and  though  the  principal  reason  that  it 
was  not  made  long  ago  is,  that  the  possibility  of  the 
question  never  occurred  to  anybody,  there  is  yet  an 
other  reason,  which  is  this  that  a  satisfactory  answer 

will  be  found  inadequate  and  unsuitable,  and  a  newer  an<i  more  appropriate 
application  of  the  terms  will  give  rise  to  confusion.  [This  is  the  case  with 
the  term  ''  analytical."]  The  analytical  method,  so  far  as  it  is  opposed  to  the 
synthetical,  is  very  different  from  that  which  constitutes  the  essence  of  ana 
lytical  propositions :  it  signifies  only  that  we  start  from  what  is  sought,  as  if 
it  were  given,  and  a?cend  to  the  only  conditions  under  which  it  is  possible. 
In  this  method  we  often  use  nothing  but  synthetical  propositions,  as  in  math 
ematical  analysis,  and  it  were  better  to  term  it  the  regressive  method,  in 
contradistinction  to  the  synthetic  or  progressive.  A  principal  part  of  Logic 
too  is  distinguished  by  the  name  of  Analytics,  which  here  signifies  the  logic 
of  truth  in  contrast  to  Dialectics,  without  considering  whether  the  cognitions 
belonging  to  it  are  analytical  or  synthetical. 


28  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

to  this  one  question  requires  a  much  more  persistent, 
profound,  and  painstaking  reflexion,  than  the  most 
diffuse  work  on  Metaphysics,  which  on  its  first  ap 
pearance  promised  immortality  to  its  author.  And 
every  intelligent  reader,  when  he  carefully  reflects 
what  this  problem  requires,  must  at  first  be  struck 
with  its  difficulty,  and  would  regard  it  as  insoluble  and 
even  impossible,  did  there  not  actually  exist  pure  syn 
thetical  cognitions  a  priori.  This  actually  happened 
to  David  Hume,  though  he  did  not  conceive  the  ques 
tion  in  its  entire  universality  as  is  done  here,  and  as 
must  be  done,  should  the  answer  be  decisive  for  all 
Metaphysics.  For  how  is  it  possible,  says  that  acute 
man,  that  when  a  concept  is  given  me,  I  can  go  be 
yond  it  and  connect  with  it  another,  which  is  not  con 
tained  in  it,  in  such  a  manner  as  if  the  latter  necessa 
rily  belonged  to  the  former?  Nothing  but  experience 
can  furnish  us  with  such  connexions  (thus  he  con 
cluded  from  the  difficulty  which  he  took  to  be  an  im 
possibility),  and  all  that  vaunted  necessity,  or^  what 
is  the  same  thing,  all  cognition  assumed  to  be  a  priori, 
is  nothing  but  a  long  habit  of  accepting  something  as 
true,  and  hence  of  mistaking  subjective  necessity  for 
objective. 

Should  my  reader  complain  of  the  difficulty  and 
the  trouble  which  I  occasion  him  in  the  solution  of 
this  problem,  he  is  at  liberty  to  solve  it  himself  in  an 
easier  way.  Perhaps  he  will  then  feel  under  obligation 
to  the  person  who  has  undertaken  for  him  a  labor  of  so 
profound  research,  and  will  rather  be  surprised  at  the 
facility  with  which,  considering  the  nature  of  the  sub 
ject,  the  solution  has  been  attained.  Yet  it  has  cost 
years  of  work  to  solve  the  problem  in  its  whole  uni 
versality  (using  the  term  in  the  mathematical  sense. 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  2Q 

viz.,  for  thai  which  is  sufficient  for  all  cases),  and 
finally  to  exhibit  it  in  the  analytical  form,  as  the 
reader  finds  it  here. 

All  metaphysicians  are  therefore  solemnly  and 
legally  suspended  from  their  occupations  till  they 
shall  have  answered  in  a  satisfactory  manner  the 
question,  "How  are  synthetic  cognitions  a  priori ^  pos 
sible?"  For  the  answer  contains  the  only  credentials 
which  they  must  show  when  they  have  anything  to 
offer  in  the  name  of  pure  reason.  But  if  they  do  not 
possess  these  credentials,  they  can  expect  nothing 
else  of  reasonable  people,  who  have  been  deceived  so 
often,  than  to  be  dismissed  without  further  ado. 

If  they  on  the  other  hand  desire  to  carry  on  their 
business,  not  as  a  science,  but  as  an  art  of  wholesome 
oratory  suited  to  the  common  sense  of  man,  they  can 
not  in  justice  be  prevented.  They  will  then  speak  the 
modest  language  of  a  rational  belief,  they  will  grant 
that  they  are  not  allowed  even  to  conjecture,  far  less 
to  know,  anything  which  lies  beyond  the  bounds  of 
all  possible  experience,  but  only  to  assume  (not  for 
speculative  use,  which  they  must  abandon,  but  for 
practical  purposes  only)  the  existence  of  something 
that  is  possible  and  even  indispensable  for  the  guid 
ance  of  the  understanding  and  of  the  will  in  life.  In 
this  manner  alone  can  they  be  called  useful  and  wise 
men,  and  the  more  so  as  they  renounce  the  title  of 
metaphysicians;  for  the  latter  profess  to  be  specula 
tive  philosophers,  and  since,  when  judgments  a  priori 
are  under  discussion,  poor  probabilities  cannot  be  ad 
mitted  (for  what  is  declared  to  be  known  a  priori  is 
thereby  announced  as  necessary),  such  men  cannot  be 
permitted  to  play  with  conjectures,  but  their  assertions 
rcust  be  either  science,  or  are  worth  nothing  at  all. 


30  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

It  may  be  said,  that  the  entire  transcendental  phi 
losophy,  which  necessarily  precedes  all  metaphysics, 
is  nothing  but  the  complete  solution  of  the  problem 
here  propounded,  in  systematical  order  and  complete 
ness,  and  hitherto  we  have  never  had  any  transcen 
dental  philosophy;  for  what  goes  by  its  name  is  prop 
erly  a  part  of  metaphysics,  whereas  the  former  science 
is  intended  first  to  constitute  the  possibility  of  the 
latter,  and  must  therefore  precede  all  metaphysics. 
And  it  is  not  surprising  that  when  a  whole  science, 
deprived  of  all  help  from  other  sciences,  and  conse 
quently  in  itself  quite  new,  is  required  to  answer  a 
single  question  satisfactorily,  we  should  find  the  an 
swer  troublesome  and  difficult,  nay  even  shrouded  in 
obscurity. 

As  we  now  proceed  to  this  solution  according  to 
the  analytical  method,  in  which  we  assume  that  such 
cognitions  from  pure  reasons  actually  exist,  we  can 
only  appeal  to  two  sciences  of  theoretical  cognition 
(which  alone  is  under  consideration  here),  pure  math 
ematics  and  pure  natural  science  (physics).  For  these 
alone  can  exhibit  to  us  objects  in  a  definite  and  actual- 
isable  form  (in  der  Anschauvtig),  and  consequently  (if 
there  should  occur  in  them  a  cognition  0/r/0r/)jcan 
show  the  truth  or  conformity  of  the  cognition  to  the 
object  in  concrete,  that  is,  its  actuality,  from  which  we 
could  proceed  to  the  reason  of  its  possibility  by  the 
analytic  method.  This  facilitates  our  work  greatly 
for  here  universal  considerations  are  not  only  applied 
to  facts,  but  even  start  from  them,  while  in  a  synthe 
tic  procedure  they  must  strictly  be  derived  in  abstracto 
from  concepts. 

But,  in  order  to  rise  from  these  actual  and  at  the 
same  time  well-grounded  pure  cognitions  a  priori  to 


METAPHYSICAL  COGNITION.  $1 

such  a  possible  cognition  of  the  same  as  we  are  seek 
ing,  viz.,  to  metaphysics  as  a  science,  we  must  com 
prehend  that  which  occasions  it,  I  mean  the  mere 
natural,  though  in  spite  of  its  truth  not  unsuspected, 
cognition  a  priori  which  lies  at  the  bottom  of  that  sci 
ence,  the  elaboration  of  which  without  any  critical  in 
vestigation  of  its  possibility  is  commonly  called  meta 
physics.  In  a  word,  we  must  comprehend  the  natural 
conditions  of  such  a  science  as  a  part  of  our  inquiry, 
and  thus  the  transcendental  problem  will  be  gradually 
answered  by  a  division  into  four  questions  : 

1 .  How  is  pure  mat  he  mat  it  s  possible ? 

2.  How  is  pure  natural  science  possible? 

3.  How  is  metaphysics  in  general  possible? 

4.  How  is  metaphysics  as  a  science  possible? 

It  may  be  seen  that  the  solution  of  these  problems, 
though  chif  fly  designed  to  exhibit  the  essential  matter 
of  the  Critique,  has  yet  something  peculiar,  which  for 
itself  alone  deserves  attention.  This  is  the  search  for 
the  sources  of  given  sciences  in  reason  itself,  so  that 
its  faculty  of  knowing  something  a  priori  may  by  its 
own  deeds  be  investigated  and  measured.  By  this 
procedure  these  sciences  gain,  if  not  with  regard  to 
their  contents,  yet  as  to  their  proper  use,  and  while 
they  throw  light  on  the  higher  question  concerning 
their  common  origin,  they  give,  at  the  same  time,  an 
occasion  better  to  explain  their  own  nature. 


FIRST  PART  OF  THE  TRANSCEN 
DENTAL  PROBLEM. 
\i 

HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE? 

§6. 

HERE  is  a  great  and  established  branch  of  knowl 
edge,  encompassing  even  now  a  wonderfully 
large  domain  and  promising  an  unlimited  extension  in 
the  future.  Yet  it  carries  with  it  thoroughly  apodeicti- 
cal  certainty,  i.  e.,  absolute  necessity,  which  therefore 
rests  upon  no  empirical  grounds.  Consequently  it  is 
a  pure  product  of  reason,  and  moreover  is  thoroughly 
synthetical.  [Here  the  question  arises  :] 

"  How  then  is  it  possible  for  human  reason  to  pro 
duce  a  cognition  of  this  nature  entirely  a  priori?" 

Does  not  this  faculty  [which  produces  mathemat 
ics],  as  it  neither  is  nor  can  be  baseu  upon  experi 
ence,  presuppose  some  ground  of  cognition  a  priori, 
which  lies  deeply  hidden,  but  which  might  reveal  it 
self  by  these  its  effects,  if  their  first  beginnings  were 
but  diligently  ferreted  out? 

§  7.  But  we  find  that  all  mathematical  cognition 
has  this  peculiarity:  it  must  first  exhibit  its  concept 
in  a  visual  form  {Anschauung}  and  indeed  a  priori, 
therefore  in  a  visual  form  which  is  not  empirical,  but 
pure.  Without  this  mathematics  cannot  take  a  single 
step ;  hence  its  judgments  are  always  visual,  viz., 


HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  33 

"intuitive";  whereas  philosophy  must  be  satisfied 
with  discursive  judgments  from  mere  concepts,  and 
though  it  may  illustrate  its  doctrines  through  a  visual 
figure,  can  never  derive  them  from  it.  This  obser 
vation  on  the  nature  of  mathematics  gives  us  a  clue 
to  the  first  and  highest  condition  of  its  possibility, 
which  is,  that  some  non-sensuous  visualisation  (called 
pure  intuition,  or  rcine  Anschauung}  must  form  its 
basis,  in  which  all  its  concepts  can  be  exhibited  or 
consti  ucted,  in  concrcto  and  yet  a  priori.  If  we  can 
find  cut  this  pure  intuition  and  its  possibility,  we  may 
thence  easily  explain  how  synthetical  propositions 
a  priori  are  possible  in  pure  mathematics,  and  conse 
quently  how  this  science  itself  is  possible.  Empirical 
intuition  [viz.,  sense-perception]  enables  us  without 
difficulty  to  enlarge  the  concept  which  we  frame  of  an 
object  of  intuition  [or  sense-perception],  by  new  pred 
icates,  which  intuition  [i.  e.,  sense  perception]  itself 
presents  synthetically  in  experience.  Pure  intuition 
[viz.,  the  visualisation  of  forms  in  our  imagination, 
from  which  every  thing  sensual,  i.  e.,  every  thought 
of  material  qualities,  is  excluded]  does  so  likewise, 
only  with  this  difference,  that  in  the  latter  case  the 
synthetical  judgment  is  a  priori  certain  and  apodeic- 
tical,  in  the  former,  only  a  posteriori  and  empirically 
certain  ;  because  this  latter  contains  only  that  which 
occurs  in  contingent  empirical  intuition,  but  the  for 
mer,  that  which  must  necessarily  be  discovered  in 
pure  intuition.  Here  intuition,  being  an  intuition  a 
priori,  is  before  all  experience,  viz.,  before  any  percep 
tion  of  particular  objects,  inseparably  conjoined  with 
its  concept. 

§  8.   But  with  this  step  our  perplexity  seems  rather 
to  increase  than  to  lessen.     For   the   question  now 


34  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

is,  "  How  is  it  possible  to  intuite  [in  a  visual  form] 
anything  a  priori?"  An  intuition  [viz.,  a  visual  sense- 
perception]  is  such  a  representation  as  immediately 
depends  upon  the  presence  of  the  object.  Hence  it 
seems  impossible  to  intuite  from  the  outset  a  priori,  be 
cause  intuition  would  in  that  event  take  place  without 
either  a  former  or  a  present  object  to  refer  to,  and  by 
consequence  could  not  be  intuition.  Concepts  indeed 
are  such,  that  we  can  easily  form  some  of  them  a 
priori,  viz.,  such  as  contain  nothing  but  the  thought 
of  an  object  in  general ;  and  we  need  not  find  our 
selves  in  an  immediate  relation  to  the  object.  Take, 
for  instance,  the  concepts  of  Quantity,  of  Cause,  etc. 
But  even  these  require,  in  order  to  make  them  under 
stood,  a  certain  concrete  use — that  is,  an  application 
to  some  sense-experience  (Anschauung},  by  which  an 
object  of  them  is  given  us.  But  how  can  the  intui 
tion  of  the  object  [its  visualisation]  precede  the  ob 
ject  itself? 

""§9.  If  our  intuition  [i.  e.,  our  sense-experience] 
were  perforce  of  such  a  nature  as  to  represent  things 
as  they  are  in  themselves,  there  would  not  be  any  in 
tuition  a  priori,  but  intuition  would  be  always  empir- 
,  ical.  For  I  can  only  know  what  is  contained  in  the  ob 
ject  in  itself  when  it  is  present  and  given  to  me.  It  is 
indeed  even  then  incomprehensible  how  the  visualis 
ing  (Anschauung)  of  a  present  thing  should  make  me 
know  this  thing  as  it  is  in  itself,  as  its  properties  can 
not  migrate  into  my  faculty  of  representation.  But 
even  granting  this  possibility,  a  visualising  of  that 
sort  would  not  take  place  a  priori,  that  is,  before  the 
object  were  presented  to  me ;  for  without  this  latter 
fact  no  reason  of  a  relation  between  my  representa- 


HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  35 

tion  and  the  object  can  be  imagined,  unless  it  depend 
upon  a  direct  inspiration. 

Therefore  in  one  way  only  can   my  intuition 
{Anscliauung}  anticipate  the  actuality  of  the  ob 
ject,  and  be  a  cognition  a  priori,  viz. :  Jf  my  intui 
tion  contains  nothing  but  the  form  of  sensibility, 
antedating  in   my  subjectivity  all  the  actual  im 
pressions  through  which  I  am  affected  by  objects. 
For  that  objects  of   sense   can  only  be  intuited  ac 
cording  to  this  form  of  sensibility  I  can  know  a  priori. 
Hence   it   follows :  that  propositions,   which   concern 
this  form  of  sensuous  intuition  only,  are  possible  and 
valid  for  objects  of  the  senses ;  as   also,  conversely, 
that  intuitions  which   are  possible  a  priori  can  never 
concern  any  other  things  than  objects  of  our  senses.1 
§  10.   Accordingly,  it  is  only  the  form  of  sensuous 
intuition  by  which  we  can  intuite  things  a  priori,  but 
by  which  we  can  know  objects  only  as  they  appear  to 
us  (to  our  senses),  not  as  they  are  in  themselves ;  and 
this  assumption  is  absolutely  necessary  if  synthetical 
propositions  a  priori  be  granted  as  possible,  or   if,  in 
case   they  actually  occur,    their    possibility   is   to   be 
comprehended  and  determined  beforehand. 

Now,  the  intuitions  which  pure  mathematics  lays 
at  the  foundation  of  all  its  cognitions  and  judgments 
which  appear  at  once  apodeictic  and  necessary  are 
Space  and  Time.  For  mathematics  must  first  have 
all  its  concepts  in  intuition,  and  pure  mathematics  in 
pure  intuition,  that  is,  jL.imi.st  construct  them.  If  it 
proceeded  in  any  other  way,  it  would  be  impossible 
to  make  any  headway,  for  mathematics  proceeds,  not 

1  This  whole  paragraph  (§9)  will  be  better  understood  when  compared 
with  Remark  I.,  following  this  section,  appearing  in  the  present  edition  on 
page  40.  —Ed. 


36  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

analytically  by  dissection  of  concepts,  but  synthetic 
ally,  and  if  pure  intuition  be  wanting,  there  is  nothing 
in  which  the  matter  for  synthetical  judgments  a  priori 
can  be  given.  Geometry  is  based  upon  the  pure  in 
tuition  of  space.  Arithmetic  accomplishes  its  concept 
of  number  by  the  successive  addition  of  units  in  time; 
and  pure  mechanics  especially  cannot  attain  its  con 
cepts  of  motion  without  employing  the  representation 
of  time.  Both  representations,  however,  are  only  in 
tuitions  ;  for  if  we  omit  from  the  empirical  intuitions 
of  bodies  and  their  alterations  (motion)  everything 
empirical,  or  belonging  to  sensation,  space  and  time 
still  remain,  which  are  therefore  pure  intuitions  that 
lie  a  priori  at  the  basis  of  the  empirical.  Hence  they 
can  never  be  omitted,  but  at  the  same  time,  by  their 
being  pure  intuitions  a  priori,  they  prove  that  they  are 
mere  forms  of  our  sensibility,  which  must  precede  all 
empirical  intuition,  or  perception  of  actual  objects, 
and  conformably  to  which  objects  can  be  known  a 
priori,  but  only  as  they  appear  to  us. 

§  ii.  The  problem  of  the  present  section  is  there 
fore  solved.  Pure  mathematics,  as  synthetical  cogni 
tion  a  priori,  is  only  possible  by  referring  to  no  other 
objects  than  those  of  the  senses.  At  the  basis  of  their 
empirical  intuition  lies  a  pure  intuition  (of  space  and 
of  time)  which  is  a  priori.  This  is  possible,  because 
the  latter  intuition  is  nothing  but  the  mere  form  of 
sensibility,  which  precedes  the  actual  appearance  of 
the  objects,  in  that  it,  in  fact,  makes  them  possible. 
Yet  this  faculty  of  intuiting  a  priori  affects  not  the 
matter  of  the  phenomenon  (that  is,  the  sense-element 
in  it,  for  this  constitutes  that  which  is  empirical),  but 
its  form,  viz.,  space  and  time.  Should  any  man  ven 
ture  to  doubt  that  these  are  determinations  adhering 


HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  $} 

not  to  things  in  themselves,  but  to  their  relation  to 
our  sensibility,  I  should  be  glad  to  know  how  it  can 
be  possible  to  know  the  constitution  of  things  a  priori, 
viz.,  before  we  have  any  acquaintance  with  them  and 
before  they  are  presented  to  us.  Such,  however,  is 
the  case  with  space  and  time.  .  But  this  is  quite  com 
prehensible  as  soon  as  both  count  for  nothing  more 
than  _formal  conditions  of  our  sensibility,  while  the 
ob]ecjts_CQunt  merely  as  phenomena  ;  for  then  the  form 
of  the  phenomenon,  i.  e.,  pure  intuition,  can  by  all 
means  be  represented  as  proceeding  from  ourselves, 
that  is,  a  priori. 

§  12.  In  order  to  add  something  by  way  of  illus 
tration  and  confirmation,  we  need  only  watch  the 
ordinary  and  necessary  procedure  of  geometers.  All 
proofs  of  the  complete  congruence  of  two  given  fig 
ures  (where  the  one  can  in  every  respect  be  substi 
tuted  for  the  other)  come  ultimately  to  this  that  they 
may  be  made  to  coincide;  which  is  evidently  noth 
ing  else  than  a  synthetical  proposition  resting  upon 
immediate  intuition,  and  this  intuition  must  be  pure, 
^pr  given  a  priori,  otherwise  the  proposition  could  not 
rank  as  apodeictically  certain,  but  would  have  em 
pirical  certainty  only.  In  that  case,  it  could  only  be 
said  that  it  is  always  found  to  be  so,  and  holds  good 
only  as  far  as  our  perception  reaches.  That  every 
where  space  (which  [in  its  entirety]  is  itself  no  longer 
:he  boundary  of  another  space)  has  three  dimensions, 
and  that  space  cannot  in  any  way  have  more,  is  based 
on  the  proposition  that  not  more  than  three  lines  can 
intersect  at  right  angles  in  one  point ;  but  this  prop 
osition  cannot  by  any  means  be  shown  from  concepts, 
but  rests  immediately  on  intuition,  and  indeed  on  pure 
and  a  priori  intuition,  because  it  is  apodeictically  cer- 


38  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

tain.  That  we  can  require  a  line  to  be  drawn  to  in 
finity  (in  indefinitum),  or  that  a  series  of  changes  (for 
example,  spaces  traversed  by  motion)  shall  be  infi 
nitely  continued,  presupposes  a  representation  of 
^pace  and  time,  which  can  only  attach  to  intuition, 
namely,  so  far  as  it  in  itself  is  bounded  by  nothing, 
for  from  concepts  it  could  never  be  inferred.  Conse 
quently,  the  basis  of  mathematics  actually  are  pure 
intuitions,  which  make  its  synthetical  and  apodeic- 
tically  valid  propositions  possible.  Hence  our  tran 
scendental  deduction  of  the  notions  of  space  and  of 
time  explains  at  the  same  time  the  possibility  of  pure 
mathematics.  Without  some  such  deduction  its  truth 
may  be  granted,  but  its  existence  could  by  no  means 
be  understood,  and  we  must  assume  "that  everything 
which  can  be  given  to  our  senses  (to  the  external 
senses  in  space,  to  the  internal  one  in  time)  is  intuited 
by  us  as  it  appears  to  us,  not  as  it  is  in  itself." 

§  13.  Those  who  cannot  yet  rid  themselves  of  the 
notion  that  space  and  time  are  actual  qualities  inher 
ing  in  things  in  themselves,  may  exercise  their  acumen 
on  the  following  paradox.  When  they  have  in  vain 
attempted  its  solution,  and  are  free  from  prejudices 
at  least  for  a  few  moments,  they  will  suspect  that  the 
degradation  of  space  and  of  time  to  mere  forms  of 
our  sensuous  intuition  may  perhaps  be  well  founded. 

If  two  things  are  quite  equal  in  all  respects  as 
much  as  can  be  ascertained  by  all  means  possible, 
quantitatively  and  qualitatively,  it  must  follow,  that 
the  one  can  in  all  cases  and  under  all  circumstances 
replace  the  other,  and  this  substitution  would  not  oc 
casion  the  least  perceptible  difference.  This  in  fact 
is  true  of  plane  figures  in  geometry;  but  some  spher 
ical  figures  exhibit,  notwithstanding  a  complete  in- 


HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  $Q 

ternal  agreement,  such  a  contrast  in  their  external 
relation,  that  the  one  figure  cannot  possibly  be  put  in 
the  place  of  the  other.  For  instance,  two  spherical 
triangles  on  opposite  hemispheres,  which  have  an  arc 
of  the  equator  as  their  common  base,  may  be  quite 
equal,  both  as  regards  sides  and  angles,  so  that  noth 
ing  is  to  be  found  in  either,  if  it  be  described  for  itself 
alone  and  completed,  that  would  not  equally  be  ap 
plicable  to  both  ;  and  yet  the  one  cannot  be  put  in  the 
place  of  the  other  (being  situated  upon  the  opposite 
hemisphere).  Here  then  is  an  internal  difference  be 
tween  the  two  triangles,  which  difference  our  under 
standing  cannot  describe  as  internal,  and  which  only 
manifests  itself  by  external  relations  in  space. 

But  I  shall  adduce  examples,  taken  from  common 
life,  that  are  more  obvious  still. 

What  can  be  more  similar  in  every  respect  and  in 
every  part  more  alike  to  my  hand  and  to  my  ear,  than 
their  images  in  a  mirror?  And  yet  I  cannot  put  such 
a  hand  as  is  seen  in  the  glass  in  the  place  of  its  arche 
type  ;  for  if  this  is  a  right  hand,  that  in  the  glass  is  a 
left  one,  and  the  image  or  reflexion  of  the  right  ear  is 
a  left  one  which  never  can  serve  as  a  substitute  for 
the  other.  There  are  in  this  case  no  internal  differ 
ences  which  our  understanding  could  determine  by 
thinking  alone.  Yet  the  differences  are  internal  as 
the  senses  teach,  for,  notwithstanding  their  complete 
equality  and  similarity,  the  left  hand  cannot  be  en 
closed  in  the  same  bounds  as  the  right  one  (they  are 
not  congruent);  the  glove  of  one  hand  cannot  be  used 
for  the  other.  What  is  the  solution?  These  objects 
are  not  representations  of  things  as  they  are  in  them 
selves,  and  as  the  pure  understanding  would  cognise 
them,  but  sensuous  intuitions,  that  is,  appearances, 


40  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

the  possibility  of  which  rests  upon  the  relation  of  cer 
tain  things  unknown  in  themselves  to  something  else, 
viz.,  to  our  sensibility.  Space  is  the  form  of  the  ex 
ternal  intuition  of  this  sensibility,  and  the  internal 
determination  of  every  space  is  only  possible  by  the 
determination  of  its  external  relation  to  the  whole 
space,  of  which  it  is  a  part  (in  other  words,  by  its  re 
lation  to  the  external  sense).  That  is  to  say,  the  part 
is  only  possible  through  the  whole,  which  is  never  the 
case  with  things  in  themselves,  as  objects  of  the  mere 
understanding,  but  with  appearances  only.  Hence 
the  difference  between  similar  and  equal  things,  which 
are  yet  not  congruent  (for  instance,  two  symmetric 
helices),  cannot  be  made  intelligible  by  any  concept, 
but  only  by  the  relation  to  the  right  and  the  left  hands 
which  immediately  refers  to  intuition. 

REMARK  I. 

Pure  Mathematics,  and  especially  pure  geometry, 
can  only  have  objective  reality  on  condition  that  they 
refer  to  objects  of  sense.  But  in  regard  to  the  latter 
the  principle  holds  good,  that  our  sense  representa 
tion  is  not  a  representation  of  things  in  themselves, 
but  of  the  way  in  which  they  appear  to  us.  Hence  it 
follows,  that  the  propositions  of  geometry  are  not  the 
results  of  a  mere  creation  of  our  poetic  imagination, 
and  that  therefore  they  cannot  be  referred  with  assu 
rance  to  actual  objects ;  but  rather  that  they  are  nec 
essarily  valid  of  space,  and  consequently  of  all  that 
may  be  found  in  space,  because  space  is  nothing  else 
than  the  form  of  all  external  appearances,  and  it  is 
this  form  alone  in  which  objects  of  sense  can  be  given. 
Sensibility,  the  form  of  which  is  the  basis  of  geom 
etry,  is  that  upon  which  the  possibility  of  external 


HOW  13  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  4! 

appearance  depends.  Therefore  these  appearances 
can  never  contain  anything  but  what  geometry  pre 
scribes  to  them. 

It  would  be  quite  otherwise  if  the  senses  were  so 
constituted  as  to  represent  objects  as  they  are  in 
themselves.  For  then  it  would  not  by  any  means  fol 
low  from  the  conception  of  space,  which  with  all  its 
properties  serves  to  the  geometer  as  an  a  priori  foun 
dation,  together  with  what  is  thence  inferred,  must 
be  so  in  nature.  The  space  of  the  geometer  would 
be  considered  a  mere  fiction,  and  it  would  not  be 
credited  with  objective  validity,  because  we  cannot 
see  how  things  must  of  necessity  agree  with  an  image 
of  them,  which  we  make  spontaneously  and  previous 
to  our  acquaintance  with  them.  But  if  this  image,  or 
rather  this  formal  intuition,  is  the  essential  property  of 
our  sensibility,  by  means  of  which  alone  objects  are 
given  to  us,  and  if  this  sensibility  represents  not 
things  in  themselves,  but  their  appearances:  we  shall 
easily  comprehend,  and  at  the  same  time  indisputably 
prove,  that  all  external  objects  of  our  world  of  sense 
must  necessarily  coincide  in  the  most  rigorous  way 
with  the  propositions  of  geometry ;  because  sensibil 
ity  by  means  of  its  form  of  external  intuition,  viz.,  by 
space,  the  same  with  which  the  geometer  is  occupied, 
makes  those  objects  at  all  possible  as  mere  appear 
ances. 

It  will  always  remain  a  remarkable  phenomenon 
in  the  history  of  philosophy,  that  there  was  a  time, 
when  even  mathematicians,  who  at  the  same  time 
were  philosophers,  began  to  doubt,  not  of  the  accuracy 
of  their  geometrical  propositions  so  far  as  they  con 
cerned  space,  but  of  their  objective  validity  and  the 
applicability  of  this  concept  itself,  and  of  all  its  corol 


42  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

laries,  to  nature.  They  showed  much  concern  whether 
a  line  in  nature  might  not  consist  of  physical  points, 
and  consequently  that  true  space  in  the  object  might 
consist  of  simple  [discrete]  parts,  while  the  space 
which  the  geometer  has  in  his  mind  [being  continu 
ous]  cannot  be  such.  They  did  not  recognise  that 
this  mental  space  renders  possible  the  physical  space, 
i.  e.,  the  extension  of  matter;  that  this  pure  space  is 
not  at  all  a  quality  of  things  in  themselves,  but  a  form 
of  our  sensuous  faculty  of  representation ;  and  that 
all  objects  in  space  are  mere  appearances,  i.  e.,  not 
things  in  themselves  but  representations  of  our  sensu 
ous  intuition.  But  such  is  the  case,  for  the  space  of 
the  geometer  is  exactly  the  form  of  sensuous  intuition 
which  we  find  a  priori  in  us,  and  contains  the  ground 
of  the  possibility  of  all  external  appearances  (accord 
ing  to  their  form),  and  the  latter  must  necessarily  and 
most  rigidly  agree  with  the  propositions  of  the  geom 
eter,  which  he  draws  not  from  any  fictitious  concept, 
but  from  the  subjective  basis  of  all  external  phenom 
ena,  which  is  sensibility  itself.  In  this  and  no  other 
way  can  geometry  be  made  secure  as  to  the  undoubted 
objective  reality  of  its  propositions  against  all  the  in 
trigues  of  a  shallow  Metaphysics,  which  is  surprised 
at  them  [the  geometrical  propositions],  because  it 
has  not  traced  them  to  the  sources  of  their  concepts. 

REMARK  II. 

Whatever  is  given  us  as  object,  must  be  given  us 
in  intuition.  All  our  intuition  however  takes  place  by 
means  of  the  senses  only;  the  understanding  intuites 
nothing,  but  only  reflects.  And  as  we  have  just  shown 
that  the  senses  never  and  in  no  manner  enable  us  to 
know  things  in  themselves,  but  only  their  appear- 


HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  43 

ances,  which  are  mere  representations  of  the  sensi 
bility,  we  conclude  that  'all  bodies,  together  with  the 
space  in  which  they  are,  must  be  considered  nothing 
but  mere  representations  in  us,  and  exist  nowhere  but 
in  our  thoughts.'  You  will  say  :  Is  not  this  manifest 
idealism  ? 

Idealism  consists  in  the  assertion,  that  there  are 
none  but  thinking  beings,  all  other  things,  which  we 
think  are  perceived  in  intuition,  being  nothing  but 
representations  in  the  thinking  beings,  to  which  no 
object  external  to  them  corresponds  in  fact.  Whereas 
I  say,  that  things  as  objects  of  our  senses  existing 
outside  us  are  given,  but  we  know  nothing  of  what 
they  may  be  in  themselves,  knowing  only  their  ap 
pearances,  i.  e. ,  the  representations  which  they  cause 
in  us  by  affecting  our  senses.  Consequently  I  grant 
by  all  means  that  there  are  bodies  without  us,  that  is, 
things  which,  though  quite  unknown  to  us  as  to  what 
they  are  in  themselves,  we  yet  know  by  the  represen 
tations  which  their  influence  on  our  sensibility  pro 
cures  us,  and  which  we  call  bodies,  a  term  signifying 
merely  the  appearance  of  the  thing  which  is  unknown 
to  us,  but  not  therefore  less  actual.  Can  this  be 
termed  idealism?  It  is  the  very  contrary. 

Long  before  Locke's  time,  but  assuredly  since 
him,  it  has  been  generally  assumed  and  granted  with 
out  detriment  to  the  actual  existence  of  external 
things,  that  many  of  their  predicates  may  be  said  to 
belong  not  to  the  things  in  themselves,  but  to  their 
appearances,  and  to  have  no  proper  existence  outside 
o  ir  representation.  Heat,  color,  and  taste,  for  in 
stance,  are  of  this  kind.  Now,  if  I  go  farther,  and  for 
weighty  reasons  rank  as  mere  appearances  the  re 
maining  qualities  of  bodies  also,  which  are  called  pri- 


44  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

mary,  such  as  extension,  place,  and  in  general  space, 
with  all  that  which  belongs  to  it  (impenetrability  or 
materiality,  space,  etc.) — no  one  in  the  least  can  ad 
duce  the  reason  of  its  being  inadmissible.  As  little 
as  the  man  who  admits  colors  not  to  be  properties  of 
the  object  in  itself,  but  only  as  modifications  of  the 
sense  of  sight,  should  on  that  account  be  called  an 
idealist,  so  little  can  my  system  be  named  idealistic, 
merely  because  I  find  that  more,  nay, 

All  the  properties  which  constitute  the  intuition  of  a 
body  belong  merely  to  its  appearance. 

The  existence  of  the  thing  that  appears  is  thereby 
not  destroyed,  as  in  genuine  idealism,  but  it  is  only 
shown,  that  we  cannot  possibly  know  it  by  the  senses 
as  it  is  in  itself. 

I  should  be  glad  to  know  what  my  assertions  must 
be  in  order  to  avoid  all  idealism.  Undoubtedly,  I 
should  say,  that  the  representation  of  space  is  not 
only  perfectly  conformable  to  the  relation  which  our 
sensibility  has  to  objects — that  I  have  said — but  that 
it  is  quite  similar  to  the  object, — an  assertion  in  which 
I  can  find  as  little  meaning  as  if  I  said  that  the  sensa 
tion  of  red  has  a  similarity  to  the  property  of  vermil 
ion,  which  in  me  excites  this  sensation. 

REMARK  III. 

Hence  we  may  at  once  dismiss  an  easily  foreseen 
but  futile  objection,  "that  by  admitting  the  ideality 
of  space  and  of  time  the  whole  sensible  world  would 
be  turned  into  mere  sham."  At  first  all  philosophical 
insight  into  the  nature  of  sensuous  cognition  was 
spoiled,  by  making  the  sensibility  merely  a  confused 
mode  of  representation,  according  to  which  we  still 
know  things  as  they  are,  but  without  being  able  to  re- 


HOW  15  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  45 

duce  everything  in  this  our  representation  to  a  clear 
consciousness ;  whereas  proof  is  offered  by  us  that 
sensibility  consists,  not  in  this  logical  distinction  of 
clearness  and  obscurity,  but  in  the  genetical  one  of 
the  origin  of  cognition  itself.  For  sensuous  percep 
tion  represents  things  not  at  all  as  they  are,  but  only 
the  mode  in  which  they  affect  our  senses,  and  conse 
quently  by  sensuous  perception  appearances  only  and 
not  things  themselves  are  given  to  the  understanding 
for  reflexion.  After  this  necessary  corrective,  an  ob 
jection  rises  from  an  unpardonable  and  almost  inten 
tional  misconception,  as  if  my  doctrine  turned  all  the 
things  of  the  world  of  sense  into  mere  illusion. 

When  an  appearance  is  given  us,  we  are  still  quite 
free  as  to  how  we  should  judge  the  matter.  The  ap 
pearance  depends  upon  the  senses,  but  the  judgment 
upon  the  understanding,  and  the  only  question  is, 
whether  in  the  determination  of  the  object  there  is 
truth  or  not.  But  the  difference  between  truth  and 
dreaming  is  not  ascertained  by  the  nature  of  the  rep 
resentations,  which  are  referred  to  objects  (for  they 
are  the  same  in  both  cases),  but  by  their  connexion 
according  to  those  rules,  which  determine  the  coher 
ence  of  the  representations  in  the  concept  of  an  ob 
ject,  and  by  ascertaining  whether  they  can  subsist  to 
gether  in  experience  or  not.  And  it  is  not  the  fault 
of  the  appearances  if  our  cognition  takes  illusion  for 
truth,  i.  e.,  if  the  intuition,  by  which  an  object  is  given 
us,  is  considered  a  concept  of  the  thing  or  of  its  exist 
ence  also,  which  the  understanding  can  only  think. 
The  senses  represent  to  us  the  paths  of  the  planets  as 
now  progressive,  now  retrogressive,  and  herein  is 
neither  falsehood  nor  truth,  because  as  long  as  we 
hold  this  path  to  be  nothing  but  appearance,  we  do 


46  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

not  judge  of  the  objective  nature  of  their  motion.  But 
as  a  false  judgment  may  easily  arise  when  the  under 
standing  is  not  on  its  guard  against  this  subjective 
mode  of  representation  being  considered  objective, 
we  say  they  appear  to  move  backward ;  it  is  not  the 
senses  however  which  must  be  charged  with  the  illu 
sion,  but  the  understanding,  whose  province  alone  it 
is  to  give  an  objective  judgment  on  appearances. 

Thus,  even  if  we  did  not  at  all  reflect  on  the  origin 
of  our  representations,  whenever  we  connect  our  in 
tuitions  of  sense  (whatever  they  may  contain),  in 
space  and  in  time,  according  to  the  rules  of  the  coher 
ence  of  all  cognition  in  experience,  illusion  or  truth 
will  arise  according  as  we  are  negligent  or  careful.  It 
is  merely  a  question  of  the  use  of  sensuous  represen 
tations  in  the  understanding,  and  not  of  their  origin. 
In  the  same  way,  if  I  consider  all  the  representations 
of  the  senses,  together  with  their  form,  space  and 
time,  to  be  nothing  but  appearances,  and  space  and 
time  to  be  a  mere  form  of  the  sensibility,  which  is  not 
to  be  met  with  in  objects  out  of  it,  and  if  I  make  use 
of  these  representations  in  reference  to  possible  ex 
perience  only,  there  is  nothing  in  my  regarding  them 
as  appearances  that  can  lead  astray  or  cause  illusion. 
For  all  that  they  can  correctly  cohere  according  to 
rules  of  truth  in  experience.  Thus  all  the  proposi 
tions  of  geometry  hold  good  of  space  as  well  as  of  all 
the  objects  of  the  senses,  consequently  of  all  possible 
experience,  whether  I  consider  space  as  a  mere  form 
of  the  sensibility,  or  as  something  cleaving  to  the 
things  themselves.  In  the  former  case  however  I  com 
prehend  how  I  can  know  a  priori  these  propositions 
concerning  all  the  objects  of  external  intuition.  Other 
wise,  everything  else  as  regards  all  possible  experience 


HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  47 

remains  just  as  if  I  had  not  departed  from  the  vulgar 
view. 

But  if  I  venture  to  go  beyond  all  possible  experi 
ence  with  my  notions  of  space  and  time,  which  I  can 
not  refrain  from  doing  if  I  proclaim  them,  qualities 
inherent  in  things  in  themselves  (for  what  should  pre 
vent  me  from  letting  them  hold  good  of  the  same 
things,  even  though  my  senses  might  be  different,  and 
unsuited  to  them?),  then  a  grave  error  may  arise  due 
to  illusion,  for  thus  I  would  proclaim  to  be  universally 
valid  what  is  merely  a  subjective  condition  of  the  in 
tuition  of  things  and  sure  only  for  all  objects  of  sense, 
viz.,  for  all  possible  experience;  I  would  refer  this 
condition  to  things  in  themselves,  and  do  not  limit  it 
to  the  conditions  of  experience. 

My  doctrine  of  the  ideality  of  space  and  of  time, 
therefore,  far  from  reducing  the  whole  sensible  world 
to  mere  illusion,  is  the  only  means  of  securing  the  ap 
plication  of  one  of  the  most  important  cognitions  (that 
which  mathematics  propounds  a  priori}  to  actual  ob 
jects,  and  of  preventing  its  being  regarded  as  mere 
illusion.  For  without  this  observation  it  would  be 
quite  impossible  to  make  out  whether  the  intuitions 
of  space  and  time,  which  we  borrow  from  no  experi 
ence,  and  which  yet  lie  in  our  representation  a  priori, 
are  not  mere  phantasms  of  our  brain,  to  which  objects 
do  not  correspond,  at  least  not  adequately,  and  con 
sequently,  whether  we  have  been  able  to  show  its  un 
questionable  validity  with  regard  to  all  the  objects  of 
the  sensible  world  just  because  they  are  mere  appear 
ances. 

Secondly,  though  these  my  principles  make  ap 
pearances  of  the  representations  of  the  senses,  they 
are  so  far  from  turning  the  truth  of  experience  into 


48  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

mere  illusion,  that  they  are  rather  the  only  means  of 
preventing  the  transcendental  illusion,  by  which  meta 
physics  has  hitherto  been  deceived,  leading  to  the 
childish  endeavor  of  catching  at  bubbles,  because  ap 
pearances,  which  are  mere  representations,  were  taken 
for  things  in  themselves.  Here  originated  the  remark 
able  event  of  the  antimony  of  Reason  which  I  shall 
mention  by  and  by,  and  which  is  destroyed  by  the 
single  observation,  that  appearance,  as  long  as  it  is 
employed  in  experience,  produces  truth,  but  the  mo 
ment  it  transgresses  the  bounds  of  experience,  and 
consequently  becomes  transcendent,  produces  nothing 
but  illusion. 

Inasmuch,  therefore,  as  I  leave  to  things  as  we 
obtain  them  by  the  senses  their  actuality,  and  only 
limit  our  sensuous  intuition  of  these  things  to  this, 
that  they  represent  in  no  respect,  not  even  in  the 
pure  intuitions  of  space  and  of  time,  anything  more 
than  mere  appearance  of  those  things,  but  never  their 
constitution  in  themselves,  this  is  not  a  sweeping  illu 
sion  invented  for  nature  by  me.  My  protestation  too 
against  all  charges  of  idealism  is  so  valid  and  clear 
as  even  to  seem  superfluous,  were  there  not  incompe 
tent  judges,  who,  while  they  would  have  an  old  name 
for  every  deviation  from  their  perverse  though  com 
mon  opinion,  and  never  judge  of  the  spirit  of  philo 
sophic  nomenclature,  but  cling  to  the  letter  only,  are 
ready  to  put  their  own  conceits  in  the  place  of  well- 
defined  notions,  and  thereby  deform  and  distort  them. 
I  have  myself  given  this  my  theory  the  name  of  tran 
scendental  idealism,  but  that  cannot  authorise  any 
one  to  confound  it  either  with  the  empirical  idealism 
of  Descartes,  (indeed,  his  was  only  an  insoluble  prob 
lem,  owing  to  which  he  thought  every  one  at  liberty 


HOW  IS  PURE  MATHEMATICS  POSSIBLE?  49 

to  deny  the  existence  of  the  corporeal  world,  because 
it  could  never  be  proved  satisfactorily),  or  with  the 
mystical  and  visionary  idealism  of  Berkeley,  against 
which  and  other  similar  phantasms  our  Critique  con 
tains  the  proper  antidote.  My  idealism  concerns  not 
the  existence  of  things  (the  doubting  of  which,  how 
ever,  constitutes  idealism  in  the  ordinary  sense),  sine;; 
it  never  came  into  my  head  to  doubt  it,  but  it  con 
cerns  the  sensuous  representation  of  things,  to  which 
space  and  time  especially  belong.  Of  these  [viz., 
space  and  time],  consequently  of  all  appearances  in 
general,  I  have  only  shown,  that  they  are  neither 
things  (but  mere  modes  of  representation),  nor  deter 
minations  belonging  to  things  in  themselves.  But 
the  word  "transcendental,'*  which  with  me  means  a 
reference  of  our  cognition,  i.  e.,  not  to  things,  but 
only  to  the  cognitive  faculty,  was  meant  to  obviate 
this  misconception.  Yet  rather  than  give  further  oc 
casion  to  it  by  this  word,  I  now  retract  it,  and  desire 
this  idealism  of  mine  to  be  called  critical.  But  if  it 
be  really  an  objectionable  idealism  to  convert  actual 
things  (not  appearances)  into  mere  representations, 
by  what  name  shall  we  call  him  who  conversely 
changes  mere  representations  to  things?  It  may.  1 
think,  be  called  "dreaming  idealism,"  in  contradis 
tinction  to  the  former,  which  may  be  called  "vision 
ary,"  both  of  which  are  to  be  refuted  by  my  transcen 
dental,  or,  better,  critical  idealism. 


SECOND  PART  OF  THE  TRANSCEN 
DENTAL  PROBLEM. 

HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE? 


ATATURE  is  the  existence  of  things,  so  far  as  it  is. 
li  determined  according  to  universal  laws.  Should 
nature  signify  the  existence  of  things  .in  themselves, 
we  could  never  cognise  it  either  a  priori  or  a  posteriori. 
Not  a  priori,  for  how  can  we  know  what  belongs  to 
things  in  themselves,  since  this  never  can  be  done  by 
the  dissection  of  our  concepts  (in  analytical  judg 
ments)?  We  do  not  want  to  know  what  is.  contained 
in  our  concept  of  a  thing  (for  the  [concept  describes 
what]  belongs  to  its  logical  being),  but  what  is  in  the 
actuality  of  the  thing  superadded  to  our  concept,  and 
by  what  the  thing  itself  is  determined  in  its  existence 
outside  the  concept.  Our  understanding,  and  the  con 
ditions  on  which  alone  it  can  connect  the  determina 
tions  of  things  in  their  existence,  do  not  prescribe 
any  rule  to  things  themselves  ;  these  do  not  conform 
to  our  understanding,  but  it  must  conform  itself  to 
them  ;  they  must  therefore  be  first  given  us  in  order 
to  gather  these  determinations  from  them,  wherefore 
they  would  not  be  cognised  a  priori. 

A  cognition  of  the  nature  of  things  in  themselves 
a  posteriori  would  be  equally  impossible.     For,  if  ex- 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  5! 

perience  is  to  teach  us  laws,  to  which  the  existence 
of  things  is  subject,  these  laws,  if  they  regard  things 
in  themselves,  must  belong  to  them  of  necessity  even 
outside  our  experience.  But  experience  teaches  us 
what  exists  and  how  it  exists,  but  never  that  it  must 
necessarily  exist  so  and  not  otherwise.  Experience 
therefore  can  never  teach  us  the  nature  of  things  in 
themselves. 

§  15.  We  nevertheless  actually  possess  a  pure  sci 
ence  of  nature  in  which  are  propounded,  a  priori  and 
with  all  the  necessity  requisite  to  apodeictical  propo 
sitions,  laws  to  which  nature  is  subject.  I  need  only 
call  to  witness  that  propaedeutic  of  natural  science 
which,  under  the  title  of  the  universal  Science  of  Na 
ture,  precedes  all  Physics  (which  is  founded  upon 
empirical  principles).  In  it  we  hive  Mathematics  ap 
plied  to  appearance,  and  also  merely  discursive  prin 
ciples  (or  those  derived  from  concepts),  which  con 
stitute  the  philosophical  part  of  the  pure  cognition  of 
nature.  But  there  are  several  things  in  it,  which  are 
not  quite  pure  and  independent  of  empirical  sources: 
such  as  the  concept  of  motion,  that  of  impenetrability 
(upon  which  the  empirical  concept  of  matter  rests), 
that  of  inertia,  and  many  others,  which  prevent  its 
being  called  a  perfectly  pure  science  of  nature.  Be 
sides,  it  only  refers  to  objects  of  the  external  sense, 
and  therefore  does  not  give  an  example  of  a  universal 
science  of  nature,  in  the  strict  sense,  for  such  a  sci 
ence  must  reduce  nature  in  general,  whether  it  regards 
the  object  of  the  external  or  that  of  the  internal  sense 
(the  object  of  Physics  as  well  as  Psychology),  to  uni 
versal  laws.  But  among  the  principles  of  this  uni 
versal  physics  there  are  a  few  which  actually  have 
the  required  universality^  for  instance,  the  proposi- 


52  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

tions  that  "substance  is  permanent/'  and  that  " every 
event  is  determined  by  a  cause  according  to  constant 
laws,"  etc.  These  are  actually  universal  laws  of  na 
ture,  which  subsist  completely  a  priori.  There  is  then 
in  fact  a  pure  science  of  nature,  and  the  question 
arises,  How  is  it  possible  ? 

§  1 6.  The  word  " nature"  assumes  yet  another 
meaning,  which  determines  the  object,  whereas  in  the 
former  sense  it  only  denotes  the  conformity  to  law 
\Gtsctzmdssigkcit\  of  the  determinations  of  the  exist 
ence  of  things  generally.  If  we  consider  it  matcrialitcr 
(i.  e.,  in  the  matter  that  forms  its  objects)  "nature  is 
the  complex  of  all  the  objects  of  experience."  And 
with  this  only  are  we  now  concerned,  for  besides, 
things  which  can  never  be  objects  of  experience,  if 
they  must  be  cognised  as  to  their  nature,  would  oblige 
us  to  have  recourse  to  concepts  whose  meaning  could 
never  be  given  in  concrcto  (by  any  example  of  possible 
experience).  Consequently  we  must  form  for  ourselves 
a  list  of  concepts  of  their  nature,  the  reality  whereof 
(i.  e.,  whether  they  actually  refer  to  objects,  or  are 
mere  creations  of  thought)  could  never  be  determined. 
The  cognition  of  what  cannot  be  an  object  of  experi 
ence  would  be  hyperphysical,  and  with  things  hyper- 
physical  we  are  here  not  concerned,  but  only  with 
the  cognition  of  nature,  the  actuality  of  which  can  be 
confirmed  by  experience,  though  it  [the  cognition  of 
nature]  is  possible  a  priori  and  precedes  all  experi 
ence. 

§  17.  The  formal  [aspect]  of  nature  in  this  nar 
rower  sense  is  therefore  the  conformity  to  law  of  all 
the  objects  of  experience,  and  so  far  as  it  is  cognised 
a  priori,  their  necessary  conformity.  But  it  has  just 
been  shown  that  the  laws  of  nature  can  never  be  cog- 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  53 

nised  a  priori  in  objects  so  far  as  they  are  considered 
not  in  reference  to  possible  experience,  but  as  things 
in  themselves.  And  our  inquiry  here  extends  not  to 
things  in  themselves  (the  properties  of  which  we  pass 
by),  but  to  things  as  objects  of  possible  experience, 
and  the  complex  of  these  is  what  we  properly  desig 
nate  as  nature.  And  now  I  ask,  when  the  possibility 
of  a  cognition  of  nature  a  priori  is  in  question,  whether 
it  is  better  to  arrange  the  problem  thus  :  How  can 
we  cognise  a  priori  that  things  as  objects  of  experi 
ence  necessarily  conform  to  law?  or  thus  :  How  is  it 
possible  to  cognise  a  priori  the  necessary  conformity 
to  law  of  experience  itself  as  regards  all  its  objects 
generally? 

Closely  considered,  the  solution  of  the  problem, 
represented  in  either  way,  amounts,  with  regard  to  the 
pure  cognition  of  nature  (which  is  the  point  of  the 
question  at  issue),  entirely  to  the  same  thing.  For 
the  subjective  laws,  under  which  alone  an  empirical 
cognition  of  things  is  possible,  hold  good  of  these 
things,  as  objects  of  possible  experience  (not  as  things 
in  themselves,  which  are  not  considered  here).  Either 
of  the  following  statements  means  quite  the  same : 

A  judgment  of  observation  can  never  rank  as  ex 
perience,  without  the  law,  that  "  whenever  an  event 
is  observed,  it  is  always  referred  to  some  antecedent, 
which  it  follows  according  to  a  universal  rule." 

"Everything,  of  which  experience  teaches  that  it 
happens,  must  have  a  cause." 

It  is,  however,  more  commendable  to  choose  the 
first  formula.  For  we  can  a  priori  and  previous  to  all 
given  objects  have  a  cognition  of  those  conditions,  on 
which  alone  experience  is  possible,  but  never  of  the 
laws  to  which  things  may  in  themselves  be  subject, 


54  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

without  reference  to  possible  experience.  We  cannot 
therefore  study  the  nature  of  things  a  priori  otherwise 
than  by  investigating  the  conditions  and  the  universal 
(though  subjective)  laws,  under  which  alone  such  a 
cognition  as  experience  (as  to  mere  form)  is  possible, 
and  we  determine  accordingly  the  possibility  of  things, 
as  objects  of  experience.  For  if  I  should  choose  the 
second  formula,  and  seek  the  conditions  a  priori,  on 
which  nature  as  an  object  of  experience  is  possible,  I 
might  easily  fall  into  error,  and  fancy  that  I  was  speak 
ing  of  nature  as  a  thing  in  itself,  and  then  move  round 
in  endless  circles,  in  a  vain  search  for  laws  concern 
ing  things  of  which  nothing  is  given  me. 

Accordingly  we  shall  here  be  concerned  with^ex- 
perience  only,  and  the  universal  conditions  of  its  pos 
sibility  which  are  given  a  priori.  Thence  we  shall 
determine  nature  as  the  whole  object  of  all  possible 
experience.  I  think  it  will  be  understood  that  I  here 
do  not  mean  the  rules  of  the  observation  of  a  nature 
that  is  already  given,  for  these  already  presuppose 
experience.  I  do  not  mean  how  (through  experience) 
we  can  study  the  laws  of  nature  ;  for  these  would  not 
then  be  laws  a  priori,  and  would  yield  us  no  pure  sci 
ence  of  nature ;  but  [I  mean  to  ask]  how  the  condi 
tions  a  priori  of  the  possibility  of  experience  are  at 
the  same  time  the  sources  from  which  all  the  uni 
versal  laws  of  nature  must  be  derived. 

§  1 8.  In  the  first  place  we  must  state  that,  while 
all  judgments  of  experience  {Erfahrungsurtheile}  are 
empirical  (i.  e.,  have  their  ground  in  immediate  sense- 
perception),  vice  versa,  all  empirical  judgments  (em- 
pirischt  Urtheile)  are  not  judgments  of  experience, 
but,  besides  the  empirical,  and  in  general  besides 
what  is  given  to  the  sensuous  intuition,  particular 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  55 

concepts  must  yet  be  superadded — concepts  which 
have  their  origin  quite  a  priori  in  the  pure  under 
standing,  and  under  which  every  perception  must  be 
first  of  all  subsumed  and  then  by  their  means  changed 
into  experience.1 

Empirical  judgments,  so  far  as  they  have  objec 
tive  validity,  are  judgments  of  experience;  but  those 
which  are  only  subjectively  valid,  I  name  mere  judg 
ments  of  perception.  The  latter  require  no  pure  con 
cept  of  the  understanding,  but  only  the  logical  con 
nexion  of  perception  in  a  thinking  subject.  But  the 
former  always  require,  besides  the  representation  of 
the  sensuous  intuition,  particular  concepts  originally 
begotten  in  the  understanding,  which  produce  the  objec 
tive  validity  of  the  judgment  of  experience. 

All  our  judgments  are  at  first  merely  judgments  of 
perception;  they  hold  good  only  for  us  (i.  e.,  for  our 
subject),  and  we  do  not  till  afterwards  give  them  a 
new  reference  (to  an  object),  and  desire  that  they 
shall  always  hold  good  for  us  and  in  the  same  way 
for  everybody  else  ;  for  when  a  judgment  agrees  with 
an  object,  all  judgments  concerning  the  same  object 
must  likewise  agree  among  themselves,  and  thus  the 
^objective  validity  of  the  judgment  of  experience  sig 
nifies  nothing  else  than  its  necessary  universality  of 
application.  And  conversely  when  we  have  reason 
to  consider  a  judgment  necessarily  universal  (which 
never  depends  upon  perception,  but  upon  the  pure 
concept  of  the  understanding,  under  which  the  per 
ception  is  subsumed),  we  must  consider  it  objective 

s~— >\ 

1  Empirical  judgments  (empirische  UrtheiU}  are  either  mere  statements 
of  fact,  viz..  records  of  a  perception,  or  statements  of  a  natural  law,  implying 
a  causal  connexion  between  two  facts.  The  former  Kant  calls  "judgments 
of  perception"  (Wa.hr nehmungsurtheile],  the  latter  "judgments  of  experi 
ence  ' '  [Rrfahrungsurtheile], — Ed, 


56  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

also,  that  is,  that  it  expresses  not  merely  a  reference 
of  our  perception  to  a  subject,  but  a  quality  of  the 
object.  For  there  would  be  no  reason  for  the  judg 
ments  of  other  men  necessarily  agreeing  with  mine,  if 
it  were  not  the  unity  of  the  object  to  which  they  all 
refer,  and  with  which  they  accord ;  hence  they  must 
all  agree  with  one  another. 

§  19.  Therefore  objective  validity  and  necessary 
^universality  (for  everybody)  are  equivalent  terms,  and 
though  we  do  not  know  the  object  in  itself,  yet  when 
we  consider  a  judgment  as  universal,  and  also  neces 
sary,  we  understand  it  to  have  objective  validity.  By 
this  judgment  we  cognise  the  object  (though  it  remains 
unknown  as  it  is  in  itself)  by  the  universal  and  neces 
sary  connexion  of  the  given  perceptions.  As  this  is 
the  case  with  all  objects  of  senst^jiufo  fronts  of  pyp^- 
r i e n ce  take  their  objective  validity  not  from  the  im 
mediate  cognition  of  the  object  fwhich  is  impossible), 
buTTrom  the  condition  of  universal  validity  in  empiri 
cal  judgments,  which,  as  already  said,  never  rests 
upon  empirical,  or,  in  short,  sensuous  conditions,  but 
upon  a  pure  concept  of_the_jjnderstanding.  The  ob 
ject  always  remajiis_unj£n^wji_in_ jtself j  but  when  hy_ 
the  concept  of  the  understanding  the  connexion_oi_the 
representations  of  the  object,  which  are  given  to  our 
sensibility,  is  determined  as  universally  valid,  the  ob- 
ject  is  determined  by  this  relation,  and  it  is  the  judg 
ment  that  is  objective. 

To  illustrate  the  matter  :  When  we  say,  ''the  room 
is  warm,  sugar  sweet,  and  wormwood   bitter,"1 — we 

1 1  freely  grant  that  these  examples  do  not  represent  such  judgments  of 
perception  as  ever  could  become  judgments  of  experience,  even  though  a 
concept  of  the  understanding  were  superadded,  because  they  refer  merely 
to  feeling,  which  everybody  knows  to  be  merely  subjective,  and  which  of 
course  can  never  be  attributed  to  the  object,  and  consequently  never  become 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  57 

have  only  subjectively  valid  judgments.  I  do  not  at 
all  expect  that  I  or  any  other  person  shall  always  find 
it  as  I  now  do;  each  of  these  sentences  only  expresses 
a  relation  of  two  sensations  to  the  same  subject,  to 
myself,  and  that  only  in  my  present  state  of  percep 
tion  ;  consequently  they  are  not  valid  of  the  object. 
Such  are  judgments  of  perception.  Judgments  of  ex 
perience  are  of  quite  a  different  nature.  What  expe 
rience  teaches  me  under  certain  circumstances,  it  must 
always  teach  me  and  everybody ;  and  its  validity  is 
not  limited  to  the  subject  nor  to  its  state  at  a  particu 
lar  time.  Hence  I  pronounce  all  such  judgments  as 
being  objectively  valid.  For  instance,  when  I  say  the 
air  is  elastic,  this  judgment  is  as  yet  a  judgment  of 
perception  only — I  do  nothing  but  refer  two  of  my 
sensations  to  one  another.  But,  if  I  would  have  it 
called  a  judgment  of  experience,  I  require  this  con 
nexion  to  stand  under  a  condition,  which  makes  it 
universally  valid.  I  desire  therefore  that  I  and  every 
body  else  should  always  connect  necessarily  the  same 
perceptions  under  the  same  circumstances. 

§  20.  We  must  consequently  analyse  experience 
in  order  to  see  what  is  contained  in  this  product  of 
the  senses  and  of  the  understanding,  and  how  the 
judgment  of  experience  itself  is  possible.  The  foun 
dation  is  the  intuition  of  which  I  become  conscious, 
J.  e.,  perception  {perceptid)>  which  pertains  merely  to 
the  senses.  But  in  the  next  place,  there  are  acts  of 
judging  (which  belong  only  to  the  understanding). 
But  this  judging  may  be  twofold — first,  I  may  merely 

objective.  I  only  wished  to  give  here  an  example  of  a  judgment  that  is 
merely  subjectively  valid,  containing  no  ground  for  universal  validity,  and 
thereby  for  a  relation  to  the  object.  An  example  of  the  judgments  of  per 
ception,  which  become  judgments  of  experience  by  superadded  concepts  of 
the  understanding,  will  be  given  in  the  next  note. 


58  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA 

compare  perceptions  and  connect  them  in  a  particular 
state  of  my  consciousness;  or,  secondly,  I  may  con 
nect  them  in  consciousness  generally.  The  former 
judgment  is  merely  a  judgment  of  perception,  and  of 
subjective  validity  only :  it  is  merely  a  connexion  of 
perceptions  in  my  mental  state,  without  reference  to 
the  object.  Hence  it  is  not,  as  is  commonly  imagined, 
enough  for  experience  to  compare  perceptions  and  to 
connect  them  in  consciousness  through  judgment; 
there  arises  no  universality  and  necessity,  for  which 
alone  judgments  can  become  objectively  valid  and  be 
called  experience. 

Quite  another  judgment  therefore  is  required  be 
fore  perception  can  become  experience.  The  given 
intuition  must  be  subsumed  under  a  concept,  which 
determines  the  form  of  judging  in  general  relatively 
to  the  intuition,  connects  its  empirical  consciousness 
in  consciousness  generally,  and  thereby  procures  uni 
versal  validity  for  empirical  judgments.  A  concept  of 
this  nature  is  a  pure  a  priori  concept  of  the  Under 
standing,  which  does  nothing  but  determine  for  an 
intuition  the  general  way  in  which  it  can  be  used  for 
judgments.  Let  the  concept  be  that  of  cause,  then  it 
determines  the  intuition  which  is  subsumed  under  it, 
e.  g.,  that  of  air,  relative  to  judgments  in  general, 
viz.,  the  concept  of  air  serves  with  regard  to  its  ex 
pansion  in  the  relation  of  antecedent  to  consequent  in 
a  hypothetical  judgment.  The  concept  of  cause  ac 
cordingly  is  a  p.ure  concept  of  the  understanding, 
which  is  totally  disparate  from  all  possible  perception, 
and  only  serves  to  determine  the  representation  sub 
sumed  under  it,  relatively  to  judgments  in  general, 
and  so  to  make  a  universally  valid  judgment  possible. 

Before,  therefore,  a  judgment  of  perception  can 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  59 

become  a  judgment  of  experience,  it  is  requisite  that 
the  perception  should  be  subsumed  under  some  such 
a  concept  of  the  understanding;  for  instance,  air 
ranks  under  the  concept  of  causes,  which  determines 
our  judgment  about  it  in  regard  to  its  expansion  as 
hypothetical.1  Thereby  the  expansion  of  the  air  is 
represented  not  as  merely  belonging  to  the  perception 
of  the  air  in  my  present  state  or  in  several  states  of 
mine,  or  in  the  state  of  perception  of  others,  but  as 
belonging  to  it  necessarily.  The  judgment,  "the  air 
is  elastic,"  becomes  universally  valid,  and  a  judgment 
of  experience,  only  by  certain  judgments  preceding 
it,  which  subsume  the  intuition  of  air  under  the  con 
cept  of  cause  and  effect:  and  they  thereby  determine 
the  perceptions  not  merely  as  regards  one  another  in 
me,  but  relatively  to  the  form  of  judging  in  general, 
which  is  here  hypothetical,  and  in  this  way  they  ren 
der  the  empirical  judgment  universally  valid. 

If  all  our  synthetical  judgments  are  analysed  so 
far  as  they  are  objectively  valid,  it  will  be  found  that 
they  never  consist  of  mere  intuitions  connected  only 
(as  is  commonly  believed)  by  comparison  into  a  judg 
ment  ;  but  that  they  would  be  impossible  were  not  a 
pure  concept  of  the  understanding  superadded  to  the 
concepts  abstracted  from  intuition,  under  which  con 
cept  these  latter  are  subsumed,  and  in  this  manner 
only  combined  into  an  objectively  valid  judgment. 

1  As  an  easier  example,  we  may  take  the  following  :  "  When  the  sun  shines 
on  the  stone,  it  grows  warm."  This  judgment,  however  often  I  and  others 
may  have  perceived  it,  is  a  mere  judgment  of  perception,  and  contains  no 
necessity;  perceptions  are  only  usually  conjoined  in  this  manner.  But  if  I 
say,  "The  sun  warms  the  stone,"  I  add  to  the  perception  a  concept  of  the 
understanding,  viz.,  that  of  cause,  which  connects  with  the  concept  of  sun 
shine  that  of  heat  as  a  necessary  consequence,  and  the  synthetical  judgment 
becomes  of  necessity  universally  valid,  viz.,  objective,  and  is  converted  from 
a  perception  into  experience. 


6o  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

Even  the  judgments  of  pure  mathematics  in  their  sim 
plest  axioms  are  not  exempt  from  this  condition.  The 
principle,  "a  straight  line  is  the  shortest  between  two 
points,"  presupposes  that  the  line  is  subsumed  under 
the  concept  of  quantity,  which  certainly  is  no  mere 
intuition,  but  has  its  seat  in  the  understanding  alone, 
and  serves  to  determine  the  intuition  (of  the  line) 
with  regard  to  the  judgments  which  may  be  made 
about  it,  relatively  to  their  quantity,  that  is,  to  plu 
rality  (as  judicia  plurativd).1  For  under  them  it  is 
understood  that  in  a  given  intuition  there  is  contained 
a  plurality  of  homogenous  parts. 

§  21.  To  prove,  then,  the  possibility  of  experience 
so  far  as  it  rests  upon  pure  concepts  of  the  understand 
ing  a  priori,  we  must  first  represent  what  belongs  to 
judgments  in  general  and  the  various  functions  of  the 
understanding,  in  a  complete  table.  For  the  pure  con 
cepts  of  the  understanding  must  run  parallel  to  these 
functions,  as  such  concepts  are  nothing  more  than  con 
cepts  of  intuitions  in  general,  so  far  as  these  are  deter 
mined  by  one  or  other  of  these  functions  of  judging, 
in  themselves,  that  is,  necessarily  and  universally. 
Hereby  also  the  a  priori  principles  of  the  possibility 
of  all  experience,  as  of  an  objectively  valid  empirical 
cognition,  will  be  precisely  determined.  For  they  are 
nothing  but  propositions  by  which  all  perception  is 
(under  certain  universal  conditions  of  intuition)  sub 
sumed  under  those  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding. 

IThis  name  seems  preferable  to  the  term  par 'ticularia,  which  is  used  for 
these  judgments  in  logic.  For  the  latter  implies  the  idea  that  they  are  not 
universal.  But  when  I  start  from  unity  (in  single  judgments)  and  so  proceed 
to  universality,  I  must  not  [even  indirectly  and  negatively]  imply  any  refer 
ence  to  universality.  I  think  plurality  merely  without  universality,  and  not 
the  exception  from  universality.  This  is  necessary,  if  logical  considerations 
shall  form  the  basis  of  the  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding.  However, 
there  is  no  need  of  making  changes  in  logic. 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  6l 


Logical  Table  of  Judgments. 

I.  2. 

As  to  Quantity.  As  to  Quality. 
Universal.  Affirmative. 

Particular.  Negative. 

Singular.  Infinite. 

3-  4- 

As  to  Relation.  As  to  Modality. 
Categorical.  Problematical. 

Hypothetical.  Assertorical. 

Disjunctive.  Apodeictical. 

Transcendental  Table  of  the  Pure  Concepts  of  the 
Understa  nding. 

I.  2. 

As  to  Quantity.  As  to  Quality. 
Unity  (the  Measure).  Reality. 

Plurality  (the  Quantity).  Negation. 

Totality  (the  Whole).  Limitation. 

3-  4- 

As  to  Relation.  As  to  M'odalily. 

Substance.  Possibility. 

Cause.  Existence. 

Community.  Necessity. 

Pure  Physiological  Table  of  the  Universal  Principles  of 
the  Science  of  Nature. 

I.  2. 

Axioms  of  Intuition.  Anticipations  of  Perception. 

3-  4- 

Analogies  of  Experience.  Postulates  of  Empirical  Thinking 

generally. 


62  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

§  210.  In  order  to  comprise  the  whole  matter  in 
one  idea,  it  is  first  necessary  to  remind  the  reader 
that  we  are  discussing  not  the  origin  of  experience, 
but  of  that  which  lies  in  experience.  The  former  per 
tains  to  empirical  psychology,  and  would  even  then 
never  be  adequately  explained  without  the  latter, 
which  belongs  to  the  Critique  of  cognition,  and  par 
ticularly  of  the  understanding. 

Experience  consists  of  intuitions,  which  belong  to 
the  sensibility,  and  of  judgments,  which  are  entirely 
a  work  of  the  understanding.  But  the  judgments, 
which  the  understanding  forms  alone  from  sensuous 
intuitions,  are  far  from  being  judgments  of  experience. 
For  in  the  one  case  the  judgment  connects  only  the 
perceptions  as  they  are  given  in  the  sensuous  intui 
tion,  while  in  the  other  the  judgments  must  express 
what  experience  in  general,  and  not  what  the  mere 
perception  (which  possesses  only  subjective  validity) 
contains.  The  judgment  of  experience  must  therefore 
add  to  the  sensuous  intuition  and  its  logical  connex 
ion  in  a  judgment  (after  it  has  been  rendered  univer 
sal  by  comparison)  something  that  determines  the 
synthetical  judgment  as  necessary  and  therefore  as 
universally  valid.  This  can  be  nothing  else  than  that 
concept  which  represents  the  intuition  as  determined 
in  itself  with  regard  to  one  form  of  judgment  rather 
than  another,  viz.,  a  concept  of  that  synthetical  unity 
of  intuitions  which  can  only  be  represented  by  a  given 
logical  function  of  judgments. 

§  22.  The  sum  of  the  matter  is  this:  the  business 
of  the  senses  is  to  intuite — that  of  the  understanding 
is  to  think.  But  thinking  is  uniting  representations 
in  one  consciousness.  This  union  originates  either 
merely  relative  to  the  subject,  and  is  accidental  and 


V*          >)• 
HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  63 

^  ^* 

subjective,  or  is  absolute,  and  is  necessary  or  objec 
tive.  Jhe__iinioii  of  representations  in  one  conscious 
ness  is  judgment.  Thinking  therefore  isTrie  same  as 
judging,  or  referring  representations  to  judgments  in 
general.  Hence  judgments  are  either  merely  subjec 
tive,  when  representations  are  referred  to  a  conscious 
ness  in  one  subject  only,  and  united  in  it,  or  objec 
tive,  when  they  are  united  in  a  consciousness  gener 
ally,  that  is,  necessarily.  The  logical  functions  of  all 
judgments  are  but  various  modes  of  uniting  represen 
tations  in  consciousness.  But  if  they  serve  for  con 
cepts,  they  are  concepts  of  their  necessary  union  in  a 
consciousness,  and  so  principles  of  objectively  valid 
judgments.  This  union  in  a  consciousness  is  either 
analytical,  by  identity,  or  synthetical,  by  the  combi 
nation  and  addition  of  various  representations  one  to 
another.  Experience  consists  in  the  synthetical  con 
nexion  of  phenomena  (perceptions)  in  consciousness, 
so  far  as  this  connexion  is  necessary.  Hence  the  pure 
concepts  of  the  understanding  are  those  under  which 
all  perceptions  must  be  subsumed  ere  they  can  serve 
for  judgments  of  experience,  in  which  the  synthetical 
unity  of  the  perceptions  is  represented  as  necessary 
and  universally  valid.1 

1  But  how  does  this  proposition,  "that  judgments  of  experience  contain 
necessity  in  the  synthesis  of  perceptions,"  agree  with  my  statement  so  often 
before  inculcated,  that  "experience  as  cognition  a  posteriori  can  afford  con 
tingent  judgments  only  ?"  When  I  say  that  experience  teaches  me  some 
thing,  I  mean  only  the  perception  that  lies  in  experience, — for  example,  that 
heat  always  follows  the  shining  of  the  sun  on  a  stone;  consequently  the 
proposition  of  experience  is  always  so  far  accidental.  That  this  heat  neces 
sarily  follows  the  shining  of  the  sun  is  contained  indeed  in  the  judgment  of 
experience  ;by  means  of  the  concept  of  cause),  yet  is  a  fact  not  learned  by 
experience;  for  conversely,  experience  is  first  of  all  generated  by  this  addi 
tion  of  the  concept  of  the  understanding  (of  cause)  to  perception.  How  per 
ception  attains  this  addition  may  be  seen  by  referring  in  the  Critique  itself 
to  the  section  on  the  Transcendental  faculty  of  Judgment  [viz.,  in  the  first 
edition,  Von  dein  Schematismus  der  reinen  Vcrttandsbegriffe\, 


64  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

§  23.  Judgments,  when  considered  merely  as  the 
condition  of  the  union  of  given  representations  in  a 
consciousness,  are  rules.  These  rules,  so  far  as  they 
represent  the  union  as  necessary,  are  rules  a  priori, 
and  so  far  as  they  cannot  be  deduced  from  higher 
rules,  are  fundamental  principles.  But  in  regard  to 
the  possibility  of  all  experience,  merely  in  relation  to 
the  form  of  thinking  in  it,  no  conditions  of  judgments 
of  experience  are  higher  than  those  which  bring  the 
phenomena,  according  to  the  various  form  of  their 
intuition,  under  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding, 
and  render  the  empirical  judgment  objectively  valid. 
These  concepts  are  therefore  the  a  priori  principles 
of  possible  experience. 

The  principles  of  possible  experience  are  then  at 
the  same  time  universal  laws  of  nature,  which  can  be 
cognised  a  priori.  And  thus  the  problem  in  our  sec 
ond  question,  "How  is  the  pure  Science  of  Nature 
possible?"  is  solved.  For  the  system  which  is  re 
quired  for  the  form  of  a  science  is  to  be  met  with  in 
perfection  here,  because,  beyond  the  above-mentioned 
formal  conditions  of  all  judgments  in  general  offered 
in  logic,  no  others  are  possible,  and  these  constitute 
a  logical  system.  The  concepts  grounded  thereupon, 
which  contain  the  a  priori  conditions  of  all  synthetical 
and  necessary  judgments,  accordingly  constitute  a 
transcendental  system.  Finally  the  principles,  by 
means  of  which  all  phenomena  are  subsumed  under 
these  concepts,  constitute  a  physical1  system,  that  is, 
a  system  of  nature,  which  precedes  all  empirical  cog 
nition  of  nature,  makes  it  even  possible,  and  hence 

l[Kant  uses  the  term  physiological  in  its  etymological  meaning  as  "per 
taining  to  the  science  of  physics,"  i.  e.,  nature  in  general,  not  as  we  use  the 
term  now  as  "  pertaining  to  the  functions  of  the  living  body."  Accordingly 
it  has  been  translated  "  physical."— Ed.\ 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  65 

may  in  strictness  be  denominated  the  universal  and 
pure  science  of  nature. 

§  24.  The  first  one1  of  the  physiological  principles 
subsumes  all  phenomena,  as  intuitions  in  space  and 
time,  under  the  concept  of  Quantity,  and  is  so  far  a 
principle  of  the  application  of  Mathematics  to  experi 
ence.  The  second  one  subsumes  the  empirical  ele 
ment,  viz.,  sensation,  which  denotes  the  real  in  intui 
tions,  not  indeed  directly  under  the  concept  of  quan 
tity,  because  sensation  is  not  an  intuition  that  contains 
either  space  or  time,  though  it  places  the  respective 
object  into  both.  But  still  there  is  between  reality 
(sense-representation)  and  the  zero,  or  total  void  of 
intuition  in  time,  a  difference  which  has  a  quantity. 
For  between  every  given  degree  of  light  and  of  dark 
ness,  between  every  degree  of  heat  and  of  absolute 
cold,  between  every  degree  of  weight  and  of  absolute 
lightness,  betw?een  every  degree  of  occupied  space 
and  of  totally  void  space,  diminishing  degrees  can  be 
conceived,  in  the  same  manner  as  between  conscious 
ness  and  total  unconsciousness  (the  darkness  of  a 
psychological  blank)  ever  diminishing  degrees  obtain. 
Hence  there  is  no  perception  that  can  prove  an  abso 
lute  absence  of  it ;  for  instance,  no  psychological 
darkness  that  cannot  be  considered  as  a  kind  of  con 
sciousness,  which  is  only  outbalanced  by  a  stronger 
consciousness.  This  occurs  in  all  cases  of  sensation, 
and  so  the  understanding  can  anticipate  even  sensa 
tions,  which  constitute  the  peculiar  quality  of  empiri 
cal  representations  (appearances),  by  means  of  the 
principle:  "that  they  all  have  (consequently  that 

IThe  three  following  paragraphs  will  hardly  be  understood  unless  refer 
ence  be  made  to  what  the  Critique  itself  says  on  the  subject  of  the  Principles; 
they  will,  however,  be  of  service  in  giving  a  general  view  of  the  Principles, 
arid  in  fixing  the  attention  on  the  main  points. 


66  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

what  is  real  in  all  phenomena  has)  a  degree."  Here 
is  the  second  application  of  mathematics  (niathesis  in- 
tensorum}  to  the  science  of  nature. 

§  25.  Anent  the  relation  of  appearances  merely 
with  a  view  to  their  existence,  the  determination  is 
not  mathematical  but  dynamical,  and  can  never  be 
objectively  valid,  consequently  never  fit  for  experi 
ence,  if  it  does  not  come  under  a  priori  principles  by 
which  the  cognition  of  experience  relative  to  appear 
ances  becomes  even  possible.  Hence  appearances 
must  be  subsumed  under  the  concept  of  Substance, 
which  is  the  foundation  of  all  determination  of  exist 
ence,  as  a  concept  of  the  thing  itself;  or  secondly— 
so  far  as  a  succession  is  found  among  phenomena, 
that  is,  an  event — under  the  concept  of  an  Effect 
with  reference  to  Cause ;  or  lastly — so  far  as  coexist 
ence  is  to  be  known  objectively,  that  is,  by  a  judg 
ment  of  experience — under  the  concept  of  Commun 
ity  (action  and  reaction).1  Thus  a  priori  principles 
form  the  basis  of  objectively  valid,  though  empirical 
judgments,  that  is,  of  the  possibility  of  experience  so 
far  as  it  must  connect  objects  as  existing  in  nature. 
These  principles  are  the  proper  laws  of  nature,  which 
may  be  termed  dynamical. 

Finally  the  cognition  of  the  agreement  and  con 
nexion  not  only  of  appearances  among  themselves  in 
experience,  but  of  their  relation  to  experience  in  gen 
eral,  belongs  to  the  judgments  of  experience.  This 
relation  contains  either  their  agreement  with  the  for 
mal  conditions,  which  the  understanding  cognises,  or 
their  coherence  with  the  materials  of  the  senses  and 
of  perception,  or  combines  both  into  one  concept. 
Consequently  it  contains  Possibility,  Actuality,  and 

1  [Kant  uses  here  the  equivocal  term  Wechseliuirkung.—Ed.} 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  67 

Necessity  according  to  universal  laws  of  nature ;  and 
this  constitutes  the  physical  doctrine  of  method,  or 
the  distinction  of  truth  and  of  hypotheses,  and  the 
bounds  of  the  certainty  of  the  latter. 

§  26.  The  third  table  of  Principles  drawn  from  the 
nature  of  the  understanding  itself  after  the  critical 
method,  shows  an  inherent  perfection,  which  raises  it 
far  above  every  other  table  which  has  hitherto  though 
in  vain  been  tried  or  may  yet  be  tried  by  analysing 
the  objects  themselves  dogmatically.  It  exhibits  all 
synthetical  a  priori  principles  completely  and  accord 
ing  to  one  principle,  viz.,  the  faculty  of  judging  in 
general,  constituting  the  essence  of  experience  as  re 
gards  the  understanding,  so  that  we  can  be  certain 
that  there  are  no  more  such  principles,  which  affords 
a  satisfaction  such  as  can  never  be  attained  by  the 
dogmatical  method.  Yet  is  this  not  all :  there  is  a 
still  greater  merit  in  it. 

We  must  carefully  bear  in  mind  the  proof  which 
shows  the  possibility  of  this  cognition  a  priori,  and  at 
the  same  time  limits  all  such  principles  to  a  condition 
which  must  never  be  lost  sight  of,  if  we  desire  it  not 
to  be  misunderstood,  and  extended  in  use  beyond  the 
original  sense  which  the  understanding  attaches  to  it. 
This  limit  is  that  they  contain  nothing  but  the  condi 
tions  of  possible  experience  in  general  so  far  as  it  is 
subjected  to  laws  a  priori.  Consequently  I  do  not 
say,  that  things  in  themselves  possess  a  quantity,  that 
their  actuality  possesses  a  degree,  their  existence  a 
connexion  of  accidents  in  a  substance,  etc.  This  no 
body  can  prove,  because  such  a  synthetical  connexion 
from  mere  concepts,  without  any  reference  to  sensu 
ous  intuition  on  the  one  side,  or  connexion  of  it  in  a 
possible  experience  on  the  other,  is  absolutely  impos- 


68  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

sible.  The  essential  limitation  of  the  concepts  in 
these  principles  then  is  :  That  all  things  stand  neces 
sarily  a  priori  under  the  afore-mentioned  conditions, 
c.s  objects  of  experience  only. 

Hence  there  follows  secondly  a  specifically  pecu 
liar  mode  of  proof  of  these  principles  :  they  are  not 
directly  referred  to  appearances  and  to  their  relations, 
but  to  the  possibility  of  experience,  of  which  appear 
ances  constitute  the  matter  only,  not  the  form.  Thus 
they  are  referred  to  objectively  and  universally  valid 
synthetical  propositions,  in  which  we  distinguish 
judgments  of  experience  from  those  of  perception. 
This  takes  place  because  appearances,  as  mere  intui 
tions,  occupying  a  part  of  space  and  time,  come  un 
der  the  concept  of  Quantity,  which  unites  their  multi 
plicity  a  priori  according  to  rules  synthetically.  Again, 
so  far  as  the  perception  contains,  besides  intuition, 
sensibility,  and  between  the  latter  and  nothing  (i.  e., 
the  total  disappearance  of  sensibility),  there  is  an 
ever  decreasing  transition,  it  is  apparent  that  that 
which  is  in  appearances  must  have  a  degree,  so  far 
as  it  (viz.,  the  perception)  does  not  itself  occupy 
any  part  of  space  or  of  time.1  Still  the  transition  to 
actuality  from  empty  time  or  empty  space  is  only 
possible  in  time;  consequently  though  sensibility,  as 


IHeat  and  light  are  in  a  small  space  just  as  large  as  to  degree  as  in  a 
large  one  ;  in  like  manner  the  internal  representations,  pain,  consciousness 
in  general,  whether  they  last  a  short  or  a  long  time,  need  not  vary  as  to  the 
degree.  Hence  the  quantity  is  here  in  a  point  and  in  a  moment  just  as  great 
as  in  any  space  or  time  however  great.  Degrees  are  therefore  capable  of  in 
crease,  but  not  in  intuition,  rather  in  mere  sensation  (or  the  quantity  of  the 
degree  of  an  intuition).  Hence  they  can  only  be  estimated  quantitatively  by 
the  relation  of  i  to  o,  viz.,  by  their  capability  of  decreasing  by  infinite  inter 
mediate  degrees  to  disappearance,  or  of  increasing  from  naught  through  in 
finite  gradations  to  a  determinate  sensation  in  a  certain  time.  Quantitas 
qualitatis  est  gradus  [i.  e.,  the  degrees  of  quality  must  be  measured  Ly 
equality]. 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLL  ?  69 

the  quality  of  empirical  intuition,  can  never  be  cog 
nised  a  priori,  by  its  specific  difference  from  other 
sensibilities,  yet  it  can,  in  a  possible  experience  in 
general,  as  a  quantity  of  perception  be  intensely  dis 
tinguished  from  every  other  similar  perception.  Hence 
the  application  of  mathematics  to  nature,  as  regards 
the  sensuous  intuition  by  which  nature  is  given  to  us, 
becomes  possible  and  is  thus  determined. 

Above  all,  the  reader  must  pay  attention  to  the 
mode  of  proof  of  the  principles  which  occur  under 
the  title  of  Analogies  of  experience.  For  these  do 
not  refer  to  the  genesis  of  intuitions,  as  do  the  prin 
ciples  of  applied  mathematics,  but  to  the  connexion 
of  their  existence  in  experience ;  and  this  can  be 
nothing  but  the  determination  of  their  existence  in 
time  according  to  necessary  laws,  under  which  alone 
the  connexion  is  objectively  valid,  and  thus  becomes 
experience.  The  proof  therefore  does  not  turn  on 
the  synthetical  unity  in  the  connexion  of  things  in 
themselves,  but  merely  of  perceptions,  and  of  these 
not  in  regard  to  their  matter,  but  to  the  determination 
of  time  and  of  the  relation  of  their  existence  in  it,  ac 
cording  to  universal  laws.  If  the  empirical  determi 
nation  in  relative  time  is  indeed  objectively  valid  (i.  e., 
experience),  these  universal  laws  contain  the  neces 
sary  determination  of  existence  in  time  generally  (viz., 
according  to  a  rule  of  the  understanding  a  priori}. 

In  these  Prolegomena  I  cannot  further  descant  on 
the  subject,  but  my  reader  (who  has  probably  been 
long  accustomed  to  consider  experience  a  mere  em 
pirical  synthesis  of  perceptions,  and  hence  not  con 
sidered  that  it  goes  much  beyond  them,  as  it  imparts 
to  empirical  judgments  universal  validity,  and  for 
that  purpose  requires  a  pure  and  a  priori  unity  of  the 


7o  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

understanding)  is  recommended  to  pay  special  atten 
tion  to  this  distinction  of  experience  from  a  mere  ag 
gregate  of  perceptions,  and  to  judge  the  mode  of  proof 
from  this  point  of  view. 

§  27.  Now  we  are  prepared  to  remove  Hume's 
doubt.  He  justly  maintains,  that  we  cannot  compre 
hend  by  reason  the  possibility  of  Causality,  that  is,  of 
the  reference  of  the  existence  of  one  thing  to  the  ex 
istence  of  another,  which  is  necessitated  by  the  for 
mer.  I  add,  that  we  comprehend  just  as  little  the 
concept  of  Subsistence,  that  is,  the  necessity  that  at 
the  foundation  of  the  existence  of  things  there  lies  a 
subject  which  cannot  itself  be  a  predicate  of  any  other 
thing ;  nay,  we  cannot  even  form  a  notion  of  the  pos 
sibility  of  such  a  thing  (though  we  can  point  out  ex 
amples  of  its  use  in  experience).  The  very  same  in 
comprehensibility  affects  the  Community  of  things,  as 
we  cannot  comprehend  how  from  the  state  of  one 
thing  an  inference  to  the  state  of  quite  another  thing 
beyond  it,  and  vice  versa,  can  be  drawn,  and  how  sub 
stances  which  have  each  their  own  separate  existence 
should  depend  upon  one  another  necessarily.  But  I 
am  very  far  from  holding  these  concepts  to  be  derived 
merely  from  experience,  and  the  necessity  represented 
in  them,  to  be  imaginary  and  a  mere  illusion  produced 
in  us  by  long  habit.  On  the  contrary,  I  have  amply 
shown,  that  they  and  the  theorems  derived  from  them 
are  firmly  established  a  priori,  or  before  all  experience, 
and  have  their  undoubted  objective  value,  though 
only  with  regard  to  experience. 

§  28.  Though  I  have  no  notion  of  such  a  connex 
ion  of  things  in  themselves,  that  they  can  either  exist 
as  substances,  or  act  as  causes,  or  stand  in  commun 
ity  with  others  (;ts  parts  of  a  real  whole),  and  I  can 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  Jl 

just  as  little  conceive  such  properties  in  appearances 
as  such  (because  those  concepts  contain  nothing  that 
lies  in  the  appearances,  but  only  what  the  under 
standing  alone  must  think):  we  have  yet  a  notion  of 
such  a  connexion  of  representations  in  our  under 
standing,  and  in  judgments  generally;  consisting  in 
this  that  representations  appear  in  one  sort  of  judg 
ments  as  subject  in  relation  to  predicates,  in  another 
as  reason  in  relation  to  consequences,  and  in  a  third  £ 
as  parts,  which  constitute  together  a  total  possible1' 
cognition.  Besides  we  cognise  a  priori  that  without 
considering  the  representation  of  an  object  as  deter 
mined  in  some  of  these  respects,  we  can  have  no  valid 
cognition  of  the  object,  and,  if  we  should  occupy  our 
selves  about  the  object  in  itself,  there  is  no  possible 
attribute,  by  which  I  could  know  that  it  is  determined 
under  any  of  these  aspects,  that  is,  under  the  concept 
either  of  substance,  or  of  cause,  or  (in  relation  to 
other  substances)  of  community,  for  I  have  no  notion 
of  the  possibility  of  such  a  connexion  of  existence. 
But  the  question  is  not  how  things  in  themselves,  but 
how  the  empirical  cognition  of  things  is  determined, 
as  regards  the  above  aspects  of  judgments  in  general, 
that  is,  how  things,  as  objects  of  experience,  can  and 
shall  be  subsumed  under  these  concepts  of  the  under 
standing.  And  then  it  is  clear,  that  I  completely  com 
prehend  not  only  the  possibility,  but  also  the  neces 
sity  of  subsuming  all  phenomena  under  these  concepts, 
that  is,  of  using  them  for  principles  of  the  possibility 
of  experience. 

§  29.  When  making  an  experiment  with  Hume's 
problematical  concept  (his  crux  metaphysicoruni},  the 
concept  of  cause,  we  have,  in  the  first  place,  given 
a  priori,  by  means  of  logic,  the  form  of  a  conditional 


.    i. 
72  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

judgment  in  general,  i.  e.,  we  have  one  given  cogni 
tion  as  antecedent  and  another  as  consequence.  But 
it  is  possible,  that  in  perception  we  may  meet  with  a 
rule  of  relation,  which  runs  thus  :  that  a  certain  phe 
nomenon  is  constantly  followed  by  another  (though 
not  conversely),  and  this  is  a  case  for  me  to  use  the 
hypothetical  judgment,  and,  for  instance,  to  say,  if 
the  sun  shines  long  enough  upon  a  body,  it  grows 
warm.  Here  there  is  indeed  as  yet  no  necessity  of 
connexion,  or  concept  of  cause.  But  I  proceed  and 
say,  that  if  this  proposition,  which  is  merely  a  subjec 
tive  connexion  of  perceptions,  is  to  be  a  judgment  of 
experience,  it  must  be  considered  as  necessary  and 
universally  valid.  Such  a  proposition  would  be,  "the 
sun  is  by  its  light  the  cause  of  heat."  The  empirical 
rule  is  now  considered  as  a  law,  and  as  valid  not 
merely  of  appearances  but  valid  of  them  for  the  pur 
poses  of  a  possible  experience  which  requires  univer 
sal  and  therefore  necessarily  valid  rules.  I  therefore 
easily  comprehend  the  concept  of  cause,  as  a  concept 
necessarily  belonging  to  the  mere  form  of  experience, 
and  its  possibility  as  a  synthetical  union  of  percep 
tions  in  consciousness  generally;  but  I  do  not  at  all 
comprehend  the  possibility  of  a  thing  generally  as  a 
cause,  because  the  concept  of  cause  denotes  a  condi 
tion  not  at  all  belonging  to  things,  but  to  experience. 
It  is  nothing  in  fact  but  an  objectively  valid  cognition 
of  appearances  and  of  their  succession,  so  far  as  the 
antecedent  can  be  conjoined  with  the  consequent  ac 
cording  to  the  rule  of  hypothetical  judgments. 

§  30.  Hence  if  the  pure  concepts  of  the  under 
standing  do  not  refer  to  objects  of  experience  but  to 
things  in  themselves  (noumena),  they  have  no  signifi 
cation  whatever.  They  serve,  as  it  were,  only  to  de- 


HOW  IS  THE   SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  73 

cipher  appearances,  that  we  may  be  able  to  read  them 
as  experience.  The  principles  which  arise  from  their 
reference  to  the  sensible  \vorld,  only  serve  our  under 
standing  for  empirical  use.  Beyond  this  they  are 
arbitrary  combinations,  without  objective  reality,  and 
we  can  neither  cognise  their  possibility  a  priori,  nor 
verify  their  reference  to  objects,  let  alone  make  it  in 
telligible  by  any  example  ;  because  examples  can  only 
be  borrowed  from  some  possible  experience,  conse 
quently  the  objects  of  these  concepts  can  be  found 
nowhere  but  in  a  possible  experience. 

This  complete  (though  to  its  originator  unex 
pected)  solution  of  Hume's  problem  rescues  for  the 
pure  concepts  of  the  understanding  their  a  priori  ori 
gin,  and  for  the  universal  laws  of  nature  their  valid 
ity,  as  laws  of  the  understanding,  yet  in  such  a  way  as 
to  limit  their  use  to  experience,  because  their  possi 
bility  depends  solely  on  the  reference  of  the  under 
standing  to  experience,  but  with  a  completely  re 
versed  mode  of  connexion  which  never  occurred  to 
Hume,  not  by  deriving  them  from  experience,  but  by 
deriving  experience  from  them. 

This  is  therefore  the  result  of  all  our  foregoing  in 
quiries  :  "  All  synthetical  principles  a  priori  are  noth 
ing  more  than  principles  of  possible  experience,  and 
can  never  be  referred  to  things  in  themselves,  but  to 
appearances  as  objects  of  experience.  And  hence 
pure  mathematics  as  well  as  a  pure  science  of  nature 
can  never  be  referred  to  anything  more  than  mere 
appearances,  and  can  only  represent  either  that  which 
makes  experience  generally  possible,  or  else  that 
which,  as  it  is  derived  from  these  principles,  must 
always  be  capable  of  being  represented  in  some  pos 
sible  experience." 


74  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

§  31.  And  thus  we  have  at  last  something  definite, 
upon  which  to  depend  in  all  metaphysical  enterprises, 
which  have  hitherto,  boldly  enough  but  always  at 
random,  attempted  everything  without  discrimination. 
That  the  aim  of  their  exertions  should  be  so  near, 
struck  neither  the  dogmatical  thinkers  nor  those  who, 
confident  in  their  supposed  sound  common  sense, 
started  with  concepts  and  principles  of  pure  reason 
(which  were  legitimate  and  natural,  but  destined  for 
mere  empirical  use)  in  quest  of  fields  of  knowledge, 
to  which  they  neither  knew  nor  could  know  any  de 
terminate  bounds,  because  they  had  never  reflected 
nor  were  able  to  reflect  on  the  nature  or  even  on  the 
possibility  of  such  a  pure  understanding. 

Many  a  naturalist  of  pure  reason  (by  which  I  mean 
the  man  who  believes  he  can  decide  in  matters  of 
metaphysics  without  any  science)  may  pretend,  that 
he  long  ago  by  the  prophetic  spirit  of  his  sound  sense, 
not  only  suspected,  but  knew  and  comprehended, 
what  is  here  propounded  with  so  much  ado,  or,  if  he 
likes,  with  prolix  and  pedantic  pomp:  "that  with  all 
our  reason  we  can  never  reach  beyond  the  field  of  ex 
perience."  But  when  he  is  questioned  about  his  ra 
tional  principles  individually,  he  must  grant,  that 
there  are  many  of  them  which  he  has  not  taken  from 
experience,  and  which  are  therefore  independent  of  it 
and  valid  a  priori.  How  then  and  on  what  grounds 
will  he  restrain  both  himself  and  the  dogmatist,  who 
makes  use  of  these  concepts  and  principles  beyond 
all  possible  experience,  because  they  are  recognised 
to  be  independent  of  it?  And  even  he,  this  adept  in 
sound  sense,  in  spite  of  all  his  assumed  and  cheaply 
acquired  wisdom,  is  not  exempt  from  wandering  in 
advertently  beyond  objects  of  experience  into  the  field 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  75 

of  chimeras.  He  is  often  deeply  enough  involved  in 
them,  though  in  announcing  everything  as  mere  prob 
ability,  rational  conjecture,  or  analogy,  he  gives  by 
his  popular  language  a  color  to  his  groundless  pre 
tensions. 

§  32.  Since  the  oldest  days  of  philosophy  inquirers 
into  pure  reason  have  conceived,  besides  the  things 
of  sense,  or  appearances  (phenomena),  which  make 
up  the  sensible  world,  certain  creations  of  the  under 
standing  (Verstandeswescn))  called  noumena,  which 
should  constitute  an  intelligible  world.  And  as  ap 
pearance  and  illusion  were  by  those  men  identified  (a 
thing  which  we  may  well  excuse  in  an  undeveloped 
epoch),  actuality  was  only  conceded  to  the  creations 
of  thought. 

And  we  indeed,  rightly  considering  objects  of  sense 
as  mere  appearances,  confess  thereby  that  they  are 
based  upon  a  thing  in  itself,  though  we  know  not  this 
thing  in  its  internal  constitution,  but  only  know  its 
appearances,  viz.,  the  way  in  which  our  senses  are 
affected  by  this  unknown  something.  The  under 
standing  therefore,  by  assuming  appearances,  grants 
the  existence  of  things  in  themselves  also,  and  so  far 
we  may  say,  that  the  representation  of  such  things  as 
form  the  basis  of  phenomena,  consequently  of  mere 
creations  of  the  understanding,  is  not  only  admissible, 
but  unavoidable. 

Our  critical  deduction  by  no  means  excludes  things 
of  that  sort  (noumena),  but  rather  limits  the  prin 
ciples  of  the  Aesthetic  (the  science  of  the  sensibility) 
to  this,  that  they  shall  not  extend  to  all  things,  as 
everything  would  then  be  turned  into  mere  appear 
ance,  but  that  they  shall  only  hold  good  of  objects  of 
possible  experience.  Hereby  then  objects  of  the  un- 


76  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

derstanding  are  granted,  but  with  the  inculcation  of 
this  rule  which  admits  of  no  exception:  "that  we 
neither  know  nor  can  know  anything  at  all  definite  of 
these  pure  objects  of  the  understanding,  because  our 
pure  concepts  of  the  understanding  as  well  as  our 
pure  intuitions  extend  to  nothing  but  objects  of  pos 
sible  experience,  consequently  to  mere  things  of  sense, 
and  as  soon  as  we  leave  this  sphere  these  concepts 
retain  no  meaning  whatever." 

§  33.  There  is  indeed  something  seductive  in  our 
pure  concepts  of  the  understanding,  which  tempts  us 
to  a  transcendent  use, — a  use  which  transcends  all 
possible  experience.  Not  only  are  our  concepts  of 
substance,  of  power,  of  action,  of  reality,  and  others, 
quite  independent  of  experience,  containing  nothing 
of  sense  appearance,  and  so  apparently  applicable  to 
things  in  themselves  (noumena),  but,  what  strength 
ens  this  conjecture,  they  contain  a  necessity  of  deter 
mination  in  themselves,  which  experience  never  at 
tains.  The  concept  of  cause  implies  a  rule,  according 
to  which  one  state  follows  another  necessarily ;  but 
experience  can  only  show  us,  that  one  state  of  things 
often,  or  at  most,  commonly,  follows  another,  and 
therefore  affords  neither  strict  universality,  nor  neces 
sity. 

Hence  the  Categories  seem  to  have  a  deeper 
meaning  and  import  than  can  be  exhausted  by  their 
empirical  use,  and  so  the  understanding  inadvertently 
adds  for  itself  to  the  house  of  experience  a  much 
more  extensive  wing,  which  it  fills  with  nothing  but 
creatures  of  thought,  without  ever  observing  that  it 
has  transgressed  with  its  otherwise  lawful  concepts 
the  bounds  of  their  use. 

§  34.     Two    important,    and    even    indispensable; 


HOW  13  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  77 

though  very  dry,  investigations  had  therefore  become 
indispensable  in  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason, — viz., 
the  two  chapters  "Vom  Schematismus  der  reinen 
Verstandsbegriffe,"  and  "Vom  Grunde  der  Unter- 
scheidung  aller  Verstandesbegriffe  iiberhaupt  in  Pha- 
nomena  und  Noumena."  In  the  former  it  is  shown, 
that  the  senses  furnish  not  the  pure  concepts  of  the 
understanding  in  concrete,  but  only  the  schedule  for 
their  use,  and  that  the  object  conformable  to  it  occurs 
only  in  experience  (as  the  product  of  the  understand 
ing  from  materials  of  the  sensibility).  In  the  latter  it 
is  shown,  that,  although  our  pure  concepts  of  the 
understanding  and  our  principles  are  independent  of 
experience,  and  despite  of  the  apparently  greater 
sphere  of  their  use,  still  nothing  whatever  can  be 
thought  by  them  beyond  the  field  of  experience,  be 
cause  they  can  do  nothing  but  merely  determine  the 
logical  form  of  the  judgment  relatively  to  given  intui 
tions.  But  as  there  is  no  intuition  at  all  beyond  the 
field  of  the  sensibility,  these  pure  concepts,  as  they 
cannot  possibly  be  exhibited  in  eoncreto,  are  void  of 
all  meaning;  consequently  all  these  noumena,  to 
gether  with  their  complex,  the  intelligible  world,1  are 
nothing  but  representation  of  a  problem,  of  which  the 
object  in  itself  is  possible,  but  the  solution,  from  the 
nature  of  our  understanding,  totally  impossible.  For 
our  understanding  is  not  a  faculty  of  intuition,  but  of 


1  We  speak  of  the  "  intelligible  world,"  not  (as  the  usual  expression  is) 
"intellectual  world."  For  cognitions  are  intellectual  through  the  under 
standing,  and  refer  to  our  world  of  sense  also;  but  objects,  so  far  as  they 
can  be  represented  merely  by  the  understanding,  and  to  which  none  of  our 
sensible  intuitions  can  refer,  are  termed '•  intelligible."  But  as  some  pos- 
si'ole  intuition  must  correspond  to  every  object,  we  would  have  to  assume  an 
understanding  that  intuites  things  immediately;  but  of  such  we  have  not  the 
least  notion,  nor  have  we  of  the  things  of  the  understanding  [Verstandes- 
v/eseiij,  to  which  it  should  be  applied. 


78  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

the  connexion  of  given  intuitions  in  experience.  Ex 
perience  must  therefore  contain  all  the  objects  for  our 
concepts ;  but  beyond  it  no  concepts  have  any  signifi 
cance,  as  there  is  no  intuition  that  might  offer  them  a 
foundation. 

§  35.  The  imagination  may  perhaps  be  forgiven 
for  occasional  vagaries,  and  for  not  keeping  carefully 
within  the  limits  of  experience,  since  it  gains  life  and 
vigor  by  such  flights,  and  since  it  is  always  easier  to 
moderate  its  boldness,  than  to  stimulate  its  languor. 
But  the  understanding  which  ought  to  think  can  never 
be  forgiven  for  indulging  in  vagaries;  for  we  depend 
upon  it  alone  for  assistance  to  set  bounds,  when  nec 
essary,  to  the  vagaries  of  the  imagination. 

But  the  understanding  begins  its  aberrations  very 
innocently  and  modestly.  It  first  elucidates  the  ele 
mentary  cognitions,  which  inhere  in  it  prior  to  all  ex 
perience,  but  yet  must  always  have  their  application 
in  experience.  It  gradually  drops  these  limits,  and 
what  is  there  to  prevent  it,  as  it  has  quite  freely  de 
rived  its  principles  from  itself?  And  then  it  proceeds 
first  to  newly-imagined  powers  in  nature,  then  to  be 
ings  outside  nature;  in  short  to  a  world,  for  whose 
construction  the  materials  cannot  be  wanting,  because 
fertile  fiction  furnishes  them  abundantly,  and  though 
not  confirmed,  is  never  refuted,  by  experience.  This 
is  the  reason  that  young  thinkers  are  so  partial  to 
metaphysics  of  the  truly  dogmatical  kind,  and  often 
sacrifice  to  it  their  time  and  their  talents,  which  might 
be  otherwise  better  employed. 

But  there  is  no  use  in  trying  to  moderate  these 
fruitless  endeavors  of  pure  reason  by  all  manner  of 
cautions  as  to  the  difficulties  of  solving  questions  so 
occult,  by  complaints  of  the  limits  of  our  reason,  and 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  79 

by  degrading  our  assertions  into  mere  conjectures. 
For  if  their  impossibility  is  not  distinctly  shown,  and 
reason's  cognition  of  its  own  essence  does  not  become 
a  true  science,  in  which  the  field  of  its  right  use  is 
distinguished,  so  to  say,  with  mathematical  certainty 
from  that  of  its  worthless  and  idle  use,  these  fruitless 
efforts  will  never  be  abandoned  for  good. 

§  36.   How  is  Nature  itself  possible? 

This  question — the  highest  point  that  transcenden 
tal  philosophy  can  ever  reach,  and  to  which,  as  its 
boundary  and  completion,  it  must  proceed — properly 
contains  two  questions. 

FIRST:  How  is  nature  at  all  possible  in  the  mate 
rial  sense,  by  intuition,  considered  as  the  totality  of 
appearances ;  how  are  space,  time,  and  that  which 
fills  both — the  object  of  sensation,  in  general  possible? 
The  answer  is :  By  means  of  the  constitution  of  our 
Sensibility,  according  to  which  it  is  specifically  affected 
by  objects,  which  are  in  themselves  unknown  to  it, 
and  totally  distinct  from  those  phenomena.  This  an 
swer  is  given  in  the  Critique  itself  in  the  transcenden 
tal  Aesthetic,  and  in  these  Prolegomena  by  the  solution 
of  the  first  general  problem. 

SECONDLY  :  How  is  nature  possible  in  the  formal 
sense,  as  the  totality  of  the  rules,  under  which  all 
phenomena  must  come,  in  order  to  be  thought  as 
connected  in  experience?  The  answer  must  be  this  : 
It  is  only  possible  by  means  of  the  constitution  of  our 
Understanding,  according  to  which  all  the  above  rep 
resentations  of  the  sensibility  are  necessarily  referred 
to  a  consciousness,  and  by  which  the  peculiar  way  in 
which  we  think  (viz  ,  by  rules),  and  hence  experience 
also,  are  possible,  but  must  be  clearly  distinguished 


8o  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

from  an  insight  into  the  objects  in  themselves.  This 
answer  is  given  in  the  Critique  itself  in  the  transcen 
dental  Logic,  and  in  these  Prolegomena,  in  the  course 
of  the  solution  of  the  second  main  problem. 

But  how  this  peculiar  property  of  our  sensibility 
itself  is  possible,  or  that  of  our  understanding  and  of 
the  apperception  which  is  necessarily  its  basis  and 
that  of  all  thinking,  cannot  be  further  analysed  or  an 
swered,  because  it  is  of  them  that  we  are  in  need  for 
all  our  answers  and  for  all  our  thinking  about  objects. 

There  are  many  laws  of  nature,  which  we  can  only 
know  by  means  of  experience  ;  but  conformity  to  law 
in  the  connexion  of  appearances,  i.  e.,  in  nature  in 
general,  we  cannot  discover  by  any  experience,  be 
cause  experience  itself  requires  laws  which  are  a  priori 
at  the  basis  of  its  possibility. 

The  possibility  of  experience  in  general  is  there 
fore  at  the  same  time  the  universal  law  of  nature,  and 
the  principles  of  the  experience  are  the  very  laws  of 
nature.  For  we  do  not  know  nature  but  as  the  total 
ity  of  appearances,  i.  e.,  of  representations  in  us,  and 
hence  we  can  only  derive  the  laws  of  its  connexion 
from  the  principles  of  their  connexion  in  us,  that  is, 
from  the  conditions  of  their  necessary  union  in  con 
sciousness,  which  constitutes  the  possibility  of  expe 
rience. 

Even  the  main  proposition  expounded  throughout 
this  section — that  universal  laws  of  nature  can  be  dis 
tinctly  cognised  a  priori — leads  naturally  to  the  prop 
osition  :  that  the  highest  legislation  of  nature  must 
lie  in  ourselves,  i.  e.,  in  our  understanding,  and  that 
we  must  not  seek  the  universal  laws  of  nature  in  na 
ture  by  means  of  experience,  but  conversely  must  seek 
nature,  as  to  Its  universal  conformity  to  law,  in  the 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE   POSSIBLE?  8 1 

conditions  of  the  possibility  of  experience,  which  lie 
in  our  sensibility  and  in  onr  understanding.  For  how 
were  it  otherwise  possible  to  know  a  priori  these  laws, 
as  they  are  not  rules  of  analytical  cognition,  but  truly 
synthetical  extensions  of  it? 

Such  a  necessary  agreement  of  the  principles  of 
possible  experience  with  the  laws  of  the  possibility  of 
nature,  can  only  proceed  from  one  of  two  reasons : 
either  these  laws  are  drawn  from  nature  by  means  of 
experience,  or  conversely  nature  is  derived  from  the 
laws  of  the  possibility  of  experience  in  general,  and 
is  quite  the  same  as  the  mere  universal  conformity 
to  law  of  the  latter.  The  former  is  self-contradic 
tory,  for  the  universal  laws  of  nature  can  and  must  be 
cognised  a  priori  (that  is,  independent  of  all  experi 
ence),  and  be  the  foundation  of  all  empirical  use  of 
the  understanding;  the  latter  alternative  therefore 
alone  remains.1 

But  we  must  distinguish  the  empirical  laws  of  na 
ture,  which  always  presuppose  particular  perceptions, 
from  the  pure  or  universal  laws  of  nature,  which, 
without  being  based  on  particular  perceptions,  con 
tain  merely  the  conditions  of  their  necessary  union 
in  experience.  In  relation  to  the  latter,  nature  and 
possible  experience  are  quite  the  same,  and  as  the 
conformity  to  law  here  depends  upon  the  necessary 
connexion  of  appearances  in  experience  (without 
which  we  cannot  cognise  any  object  whatever  in  the 
sensible  world),  consequently  upon  the  original  laws 

1  Crusius  alone  thought  of  a  compromise  :  that  a  Spirit,  who  can  neither 
err  nor  deceive,  implanted  these  laws  in  us  originally.  But  since  false  prin 
ciples  often  intrude  themselves,  as  indeed  the  very  system  of  this  man  shows 
in  not  a  few  examples,  we  are  involved  in  difficulties  as  to  the  use  of  such  a 
principle  in  the  absence  of  sure  criteria  to  distinguish  the  genuine  origin 
from  the  spurious,  as  vye  never  can  know  certainly  what  the  Spirit  of  truth 
or  the  father  of  lies  may  have  instilled  into  us. 


82  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

of  the  understanding,  it  seems  at  first  strange,  but  is 
not  the  less  certain,  to  say: 

The  understanding  does  not  derive  its  laws  (a  priori} 
from,  but  prescribes  them  to,  nature. 

§  37-  We  shall  illustrate  this  seemingly  bold  prop 
osition  by  an  example,  which  will  show,  that  laws, 
which  we  discover  in  objects  of  sensuous  intuition 
(especially  when  these  laws  are  cognised  as  neces 
sary),  are  commonly  held  by  us  to  be  such  as  have 
been  placed  there  by  the  understanding,  in  spite  of 
their  being  similar  in  all  points  to  the  laws  of  nature, 
which  we  ascribe  to  experience. 

§  38.  If  we  consider  the  properties  of  the  circle, 
by  which  this  figure  combines  so  many  arbitrary  de 
terminations  of  space  in  itself,  at  once  in  a  universal 
rule,  we  cannot  avoid  attributing  a  constitution  (eine 
Natur}  to  this  geometrical  thing.  Two  right  lines, 
for  example,  which  intersect  one  another  and  the 
circle,  howsoever  they  may  be  drawn,  are  always  di 
vided  so  that  the  rectangle  constructed  with  the  seg 
ments  of  the  one  is  equal  to  that  constructed  with  the 
segments  of  the  other.  The  question  now  is :  Does 
this  law  lie  in  the  circle  or  in  the  understanding,  that 
is,  Does  this  figure,  independently  of  the  understand 
ing,  contain  in  itself  the  ground  of  the  law,  or  does 
the  understanding,  having  constructed  according  to 
its  concepts  (according  to  the  quality  of  the  radii)  the 
figure  itself,  introduce  into  it  this  law  of  the  chords 
cutting  one  another  in  geometrical  proportion?  When 
we  follow  the  proofs  of  this  law,  we  soon  perceive, 
that  it  can  only  be  derived  from  the  condition  on 
which  the  understanding  founds  the  construction  of 
this  figure,  and  which  is  that  of  the  equality  of  the 
radii.  But,  if  we  enlarge  this  concept,  to  pursue  fur- 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE   POSSIBLE?  83 

ther  the  unity  of  various  properties  of  geometrical 
figures  under  common  laws,  and  consider  the  circle 
as  a  conic  section,  which  of  course  is  subject  to  the 
same  fundamental  conditions  of  construction  as  other 
conic  sections,  we  shall  find  that  all  the  chords  which 
intersect  within  the  ellipse,  parabola,  and  hyperbola, 
always  intersect  so  that  the  rectangles  of  their  seg 
ments  are  not  indeed  equal,  but  always  bear  a  con 
stant  ratio  to  one  another.  If  we  proceed  still  farther, 
to  the  fundamental  laws  of  physical  astronomy,  we 
find  a  physical  law  of  reciprocal  attraction  diffused 
over  all  material  nature,  the  rule  of  which  is:  "that  it 
decreases  inversely  as  the  square  of  the  distance  from 
each  attracting  point,  i.  e. ,  as  the  spherical  surfaces 
increase,  over  which  this  force  spreads,"  which  law 
seems  to  be  necessarily  inherent  in  the  very  nature  of 
things,  and  hence  is  usually  propounded  as  cognis 
able  a  priori.  Simple  as  the  sources  of  this  law  are, 
merely  resting  upon  the  relation  of  spherical  surfaces 
of  different  radii,  its  consequences  are  so  valuable 
with  regard  to  the  variety  of  their  agreement  and  its 
regularity,  that  not  only  are  all  possible  orbits  of  the 
celestial  bodies  conic  sections,  but  such  a  relation  of 
these  orbits  to  each  other  results,  that  no  other  law 
of  attraction,  than  that  of  the  inverse  square  of  the 
distance,  can  be  imagined  as  fit  for  a  cosmical  system. 

Here  accordingly  is  a  nature  that  rests  upon  laws 
which  the  understanding  cognises  a  priori,  and  chiefly 
from  the  universal  principles  of  the  determination  of 
space.  Now  I  ask  : 

Do  the  laws  of  nature  lie  in  space,  and  does  the 
understanding  learn  them  by  merely  endeavoring  to 
find  out  the  enormous  wealth  of  meaning  that  lies  in 
space  ;  or  do  they  inhere  in  the  understanding  and  in 


84  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

the  way  in  which  it  determines  space  according  to  the 
conditions  of  the  synthetical  unity  in  which  its  con 
cepts  are  all  centred? 

Space  is  something  so  uniform  and  as  to  all  par 
ticular  properties  so  indeterminate,  that  we  should 
certainly  not  seek  a  store  of  laws  of  nature  in  it. 
Whereas  that  which  determines  space  to  assume  the 
form  of  a  circle  or  the  figures  of  a  cone  and  a  sphere, 
is  the  understanding,  so  far  as  it  contains  the  ground 
of  the  unity  of  their  constructions. 

The  mere  universal  form  of  intuition,  called  space, 
must  therefore  be  the  substratum  of  all  intuitions  de- 
terminable  to  particular  objects,  and  in  it  of  course 
the  condition  of  the  possibility  and  of  the  variety  of 
these  intuitions  lies.  But  the  unity  of  the  objects  is 
entirely  determined  by  the  understanding,  and  on 
conditions  which  lie  in  its  own  nature  ;  and  thus  the 
understanding  is  the  origin  of  the  universal  order  of 
nature,  in  that  it  comprehends  all  appearances  under 
its  own  laws,  and  thereby  first  constructs,  a  priori, 
experience  (as  to  its  form),  by  means  of  which  what 
ever  is  to  be  cognised  only  by  experience,  is  necessa 
rily  subjected  to  its  laws.  For  we  are  not  now  con 
cerned  with  the  nature  of  things  in  themselves,  which 
is  independent  of  the  conditions  both  of  our  sensi 
bility  and  our  understanding,  but  with  nature,  as  an 
object  of  possible  experience,  and  in  this  case  the 
understanding,  whilst  it  makes  experience  possible, 
thereby  insists  that  the  sensuous  world  is  either  not 
an  object  of  experience  at  all,  or  must  be  nature  [viz., 
an  existence  of  things,  determined  according  to  uni 
versal  laws1]. 

IThe  definition  of  nature  is  given  in  the  beginning  of  the  Second  Part  of 
the  "  Transcendental  Pioblenj,"  in  §  14. 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE  POSSIBLE?  85 


APPENDIX  TO  THE  PURE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE. 

§  39-    Of  the  System  of  the  Categories, 

There  can  be  nothing  more  desirable  to  a  philos 
opher,  than  to  be  able  to  derive  the  scattered  multi 
plicity  of  the  concepts  or  the  principles,  which  had 
occurred  to  him  in  concrete  use,  from  a  principle 
a  priori,  and  to  unite  everything  in  this  way  in  one 
cognition.  He  formerly  only  believed  that  those 
things,  which  remained  after  a  certain  abstraction, 
and  seemed  by  comparison  among  one  another  to 
constitute  a  particular  kind  of  cognitions,  were  com 
pletely  collected  ;  but  this  was  only  an  Aggregate. 
Now  he  knows,  that  just  so  many,  neither  more  nor 
less,  can  constitute  the  mode  of  cognition,  and  per 
ceives  the  necessity  of  his  division,  which  constitutes 
comprehension;  and  now  only  he  has  attained  a 
System. 

To  search  in  our  daily  cognition  for  the  concepts, 
which  do  not  rest  upon  particular  experience,  and  yet 
occur  in  all  cognition  of  experience,  where  they  as  it 
were  constitute  the  mere  form  of  connexion,  presup 
poses  neither  greater  reflexion  nor  deeper  insight, 
than  to  detect  in  a  language  the  rules  of  the  actual 
use  of  words  generally,  and  thus  to  collect  elements 
for  a  grammar.  In  fact  both  researches  are  very 
nearly  related,  even  though  we  are  not  able  to  give  a 
reason  why  each  language  has  just  this  and  no  other 
formal  constitution,  and  still  less  why  an  exact  number 
of  such  formal  determinations  in  general  are  found 
in  it. 


86  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

Aristotle  collected  ten  pure  elementary  concepts 
under  the  name  of  Categories.1  To  these,  which  are 
also  called  predicaments,  he  found  himself  obliged 
afterwards  to  add  five  post-predicaments,2  some  of 
which  however  (prius,  simul,  and  motus}  are  contained 
in  the  former;  but  this  random  collection  must  be 
considered  (and  commended)  as  a  mere  hint  for  future 
inquirers,  not  as  a  regularly  developed  idea,  and  hence 
it  has,  in  the  present  more  advanced  state  of  philoso 
phy,  been  rejected  as  quite  useless. 

After  long  reflexion  on  the  pure  elements  of  human 
knowledge  (those  which  contain  nothing  empirical),  I 
at  last  succeeded  in  distinguishing  with  certainty  and 
in  separating  the  pure  elementary  notions  of  the  Sen 
sibility  (space  and  time)  from  those  of  the  Under 
standing.  Thus  the  yth,  8th,  and  Qth  Categories  had 
to  be  excluded  from  the  old  list.  And  the  others  were 
of  no  service  to  me ;  because  there  was  no  principle 
[in  them],  on  which  the  understanding  could  be  inves 
tigated,  measured  in  its  completion,  and  all  the  func 
tions,  whence  its  pure  concepts  arise,  determined  ex 
haustively  and  with  precision. 

But  in  order  to  discover  such  a  principle,  I  looked 
about  for  an  act  of  the  understanding  which  comprises 
all  the  rest,  and  is  distinguished  only  by  various  modi 
fications  or  phases,  in  reducing  the  multiplicity  of 
representation  to  the  unity  of  thinking  in  general :  I 
found  this  act  of  the  understanding  to  consist  in  judg 
ing.  Here  then  the  labors  of  the  logicians  were  ready 
at  hand,  though  not  yet  quite  free  from  defects,  and 
with  this  help  I  was  enabled  to  exhibit  a  complete 

1  t  Substantia.  i.  Qualitas.  3.  Quantitas.  4.  Relatio.  5.  Actio.  6.  Pastio. 
7.  Quando.  8.  Ubi.  9.  Situs.  10.  Habitus. 

lOppositum.     Prz'us.     Szntul.     Motus.     Habere. 


HOW  IS  THE  SCIENCE  OF  NATURE   POSSIBLE  ?  87 

table  of  the  pure  functions  of  the  understanding, 
which  are  however  undetermined  in  regard  to  any  ob 
ject.  I  finally  referred  these  functions  of  judging  to 
objects  in  general,  or  rather  to  the  condition  of  deter 
mining  judgments  as  objectively  valid,  and  so  there 
arose  the  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding,  con 
cerning  which  I  could  make  certain,  that  these,  and 
this  exact  number  only,  constitute  our  whole  cogni 
tion  of  tilings  from  pure  understanding.  I  was  justi 
fied  in  calling  them  by  their  old  name,  Categories, 
while  I  reserved  for  myself  the  liberty  of  adding,  un 
der  the  title  of  "Predicables, "  a  complete  list  of  all 
the  concepts  deducible  from  them,  by  combinations 
whether  among  themselves,  or  with  the  pure  form  of 
the  appearance,  i.  e.,  space  or  time,  or  with  its  mat 
ter,  so  far  as  it  is  not  yet  empirically  determined  (viz., 
the  object  of  sensation  in  general),  as  soon  as  a  sys 
tem  of  transcendental  philosophy  should  be  completed 
with  the  construction  of  which  I  am  engaged  in  the 
Critique  of  Pure  Reason  itself. 

Now  the  essential  point  in  this  system  of  Catego 
ries,  which  distinguishes  it  from  the  old  rhapsodical 
collection  without  any  principle,  and  for  which  alone 
it  deserves  to  be  considered  as  philosophy,  consists 
in  this:  that  by  means  of  it  the  true  significance  of 
the  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding  and  the  con 
dition  of  their  use  could  be  precisely  determined.  For 
here  it  became  obvious  that  they  are  themselves  noth 
ing  but  logical  functions,  and  as  such  do  not  produce 
the  least  concept  of  an  object,  but  require  some  sen 
suous  intuition  as  a  basis.  They  therefore  only  serve 
to  determine  empirical  judgments,  which  are  other 
wise  undetermined  and  indifferent  as  regards  all  func 
tions  of  judging,  relatively  to  these  functions,  thereby 


KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

procuring  them  universal  validity,  and  by  means  of 
them  making  judgments  of  experience  in  general  pos 
sible. 

Such  an  insight  into  the  nature  of  the  categories, 
which  limits  them  at  the  same  time  to  the  mere  use  of 
experience,  never  occurred  either  to  their  first  author, 
or  to  any  of  his  successors;  but  without  this  insight 
(which  immediately  depends  upon  their  derivation  or 
deduction),  they  are  quite  useless  and  only  a  miser 
able  list  of  names,  without  explanation  or  rule  for 
their  u-se.  Had  the  ancients  ever  conceived  such  a 
notion,  doubtless  the  whole  study  of  the  pure  rational 
knowledge,  which  under  the  name  of  metaphysics  has 
for  centuries  spoiled  many  a  sound  mind,  would  have 
reached  us  in  quite  another  shape,  and  would  have 
enlightened  the  human  understanding,  instead  of 
actually  exhausting  it  in  obscure  and  vain  specula 
tions,  thereby  rendering  it  unfit  for  true  science. 

This  system  of  categories  makes  all  treatment  of 
every  object  of  pure  reason  itself  systematic,  and 
affords  a  direction  or  clue  how  and  through  what 
points  of  inquiry  every  metaphysical  consideration 
must  proceed,  in  order  to  be  complete ;  for  it  exhausts 
all  the  possible  movements  {momenta}  of  the  under 
standing,  among  which  every  concept  must  be  classed. 
In  like  manner  the  table  of  Principles  has  been  formu 
lated,  the  completeness  of  which  we  can  only  vouch 
for  by  the  system  of  the  categories.  Even  in  the  divi 
sion  of  the  concepts,1  which  must  go  beyond  the  phys 
ical  application  of  the  understanding,  it  is  always  the 
very  same  clue,  which,  as  it  must  always  be  deter- 

1  See  the  two  tables  in  the  chapters  Von  den  Paralogisnten  der  rei'nen  Ver- 
nunft  and  the  first  division  of  the  Antinomy  of  Pure  Reason,  System  der  kos- 
mologischen  Ideen. 


HOW  IS    HIE   SCIKNCE  OF  NATURE    POSSIBLE?  89 

mined  a  priority  the  same  fixed  points  of  the  human 
understanding,  always  forms  a  closed  circle.  There 
is  no  doubt  that  the  object  of  a  pure  conception  either 
of  the  understanding  or  of  reason,  so  far  as  it  is  to  be 
estimated  philosophically  and  on  a  priori  principles, 
can  in  this  way  be  completely  cognised.  I  could  not 
therefore  omit  to  make  use  of  this  clue  with  regard  to 
one  of  the  most  abstract  ontological  divisions,  viz., 
the  various  distinctions  of  "the  notions  of  something 
and  of  nothing,"  and  to  construct  accordingly  (Cri 
tique  t  p.  207)  a  regular  and  necessary  table  of  their 
divisions.1 

And  this  system,  like  every  other  true  one  founded 
on  a  universal  principle,  shows  its  inestimable  value 
in  this,  that  it  excludes  all  foreign  concepts,  which 
might  otherwise  intrude  among  the  pure  concepts  of 
the  understanding,  and  determines  the  place  of  every 
cognition.  Those  concepts,  which  under  the  name  of 
"concepts  of  reflexion"  have  been  likewise  arranged 
in  a  table  according  to  the  clue  of  the  categories,  in 
trude,  without  having  any  privilege  or  title  to  be 

1  On  the  table  of  the  categories  many  neat  observations  may  be  made,  for 
instance  :  (i)  that  the  third  arises  from  the  first  and  the  second  joined  in  one 
concept;  (2)  that  in  those  of  Quantity  and  of  Quality  there  is  merely  a  pro 
gress  from  unity  to  totality  or  from  something  to  nothing  (for  this  purpose 
the  categories  of  Quality  must  stand  thus  :  reality,  limitation,  total  negation), 
without  correlita  or  opposita,  whereas  those  of  Relation  and  of  Mcdality  have 
them  ;  (3)  that,  as  in  Logic  categorical  judgments  are  the  basis  of  all  others, 
so  the  category  of  Substance  is  the  basis  of  all  concepts  of artual things; 
(4)  that  as  Modality  in  the  judgment  is  not  a  particular  predicate,  FO  by  the 
modal  concepts  a  determination  is  not  superadded  to  things,  etc.,  etc  Such 
observations  are  of  great  use.  If  we  besides  enumerate  all  the  predicables, 
which  we  can  find  pretty  completely  in  any  good  ontology  (for  example, 
Baumgarten's),  and  arrange  them  in  classes  under  the  categories,  in  which 
operation  we  must  not  neglect  to  add  as  complete  a  dissection  of  all  these 
concepts  as  possible,  there  will  then  arise  a  merely  analytical  part  of  meta 
physics,  which  does  not  contain  a  single  synthetical  proposition,  which 
might  precede  the  second  (the  synthetical),  and  would  by  its  precision  and 
completeness  be  not  only  useful,  but,  in  virtue  of  its  system,  be  even  to  some 
extent  elegant. 


go  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

among  the  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding  in  On 
tology.  They  are  concepts  of  connexion,  and  thereby 
ol  the  objects  themselves,  whereas  the  former  are  only 
concepts  of  a  mere  comparison  of  concepts  already 
given,  hence  of  quite  another  nature  and  use.  By 
my  systematic  division1  they  are  saved  from  this  con 
fusion.  But  the  value  of  my  special  table  of  the  cate 
gories  will  be  still  more  obvious,  when  we  separate  the 
table  of  the  transcendental  concepts  of  Reason  from 
the  concepts  of  the  understanding.  The  latter  being 
of  quite  another  nature  and  origin,  they  must  have 
quite  another  form  than  the  former.  This  so  neces 
sary  separation  has  never  yet  been  made  in  any  sys 
tem  of  metaphysics  for,  as  a  rule,  these  rational  con 
cepts  all  mixed  up  with  the  categories,  like  children 
of  one  family,  which  confusion  was  unavoidable  in  the 
absence  of  a  definite  system  of  categories. 

1  See  Critique  of  Pure  Reason,   Von  der  Amphibolic  der  Reflexbegriffe. 


THIRD  PART  OF  THE  MAIN  TRAN 
SCENDENTAL  PROBLEM. 

HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE? 

§  4°- 

PURE  mathematics  and  pure  science  of  nature  had 
no  occasion  for  such  a  deduction,  as  we  have 
made  of  both,  for  their  own  safety  and  certainty.  For 
the  former  rests  upon  its  own  evidence  ;  and  the  latter 
(though  sprung  from  pure  sources  of  the  understand 
ing)  upon  experience  and  its  thorough  confirmation. 
Physics  cannot  altogether  refuse  and  dispense  with 
the  testimony  of  the  latter;  because  with  all  its  cer 
tainty,  it  can  never,  as  philosophy,  rival  mathemat 
ics.  Both  sciences  therefore  stood  in  need  of  this  in 
quiry,  not  for  themselves,  but  for  the  sake  of  another 
science,  metaphysics. 

Metaphysics  has  to  do  not  only  with  concepts  of 
nature,  which  always  find  their  application  in  experi 
ence,  but  also  with  pure  rational  concepts,  which 
never  can  be  given  in  any  possible  experience.  Con 
sequently  the  objective  reality  of  these  concepts  (viz., 
that  they  are  not  mere  chimeras),  and  the  truth  or 
falsity  of  metaphysical  assertions,  cannot  be  discov 
ered  or  confirmed  by  any  experience.  This  part  of 
metaphysics  however  is  precisely  what  constitutes  its 
essential  end,  to  which  the  rest  is  only  a  means,  and 


92  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

thus  this  science  is  in  need  of  such  a  deduction  for  its 
own  sake.  The  third  question  now  proposed  relates 
therefore  as  it  were  to  the  root  and  essential  difference 
of  metaphysics,  i.  e.,  the  occupation  of  Reason  with 
itself,  and  the  supposed  knowledge  of  objects  arising 
immediately  from  this  incubation  of  its  own  concepts, 
without  requiring,  or  indeed  being  able  to  reach  that 
knowledge  through,  experience.1 

Without  solving  this  problem  reason  never  is  jus 
tified.  The  empirical  use  to  which  reason  limits  the 
pure  understanding,  does  not  fully  satisfy  the  proper 
destination  of  the  latter.  Every  single  experience  is 
only  a  part  of  the  whole  sphere  of  its  domain,  but  the 
absolute  totality  of  all  possible  experience  is  itself  not 
experience.  Yet  it  is  a  necessary  [concrete]  problem 
for  reason,  the  mere  representation  of  which  requires 
concepts  quite  different  from  the  categories,  whose 
use  is  only  immanent,  or  refers  to  experience,  so  far 
as  it  can  be  given.  Whereas  the  concepts  of  reason 
aim  at  the  completeness,  i.  e.,  the  collective  unity  of 
all  possible  experience,  and  thereby  transcend  every 
given  experience.  Thus  they  become  transcendent. 

As  the  understanding  stands  in  need  of  categories 
for  experience,  reason  contains  in  itself  the  source 
of  ideas,  by  which  I  mean  necessary  concepts,  whose 
object  cannot  be  given  in  any  experience.  The  latter 
are  inherent  in  the  nature  of  reason,  as  the  former 
are  in  that  of  the  understanding.  While  the  former 
carry  with  them  an  illusion  likely  to  mislead,  the  illu- 


1  If  we  c.in  say,  that  a  science  is  actual  at  least  in  the  idea  of  all  men,  as 
soon  as  it  appears  that  the  problems  which  lead  to  it  are  proposed  to  every 
body  by  the  nature  of  human  reason,  and  that  therefore  many  (though  faulty) 
endravors  are  unavoidably  made  in  its  behalf,  then  we  are  bound  to  ?ay  thnt 
metaphysics  is  s-ihjeriively  (a;:d  indeed  necessarily)  actual,  and  therefore 
we  justly  ask,  h^w  is  ii  .^objectively)  possible. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?  93 

sion  of  the  latter  is  inevitable,  though  it  certainly  can 
be  kept  from  misleading  us. 

Since  all  illusion  consists  in  holding  the  subjective 
ground  of  our  judgments  to  be  objective,  a  self- 
knowledge  of  pure  reason  in  its  transcendent  (ex 
aggerated)  use  is  the  sole  preservative  from  the  aber 
rations  into  which  reason  falls  when  it  mistakes  its 
destination,  and  refers  that  to  the  object  transcen- 
dently,  which  only  regards  its  own  subject  and  its 
guidance  in  all  immanent  use. 

§  41.  The  distinction  of  ideas,  that  is,  of  pure 
concepts  of  reason,  from  categories,  or  pure  concepts 
of  the  understanding,  as  cognitions  of  a  quite  distinct 
species,  origin  and  use,  is  so  important  a  point  in 
founding  a  science  which  is  to  contain  the  system  of 
all  these  a  priori  cognitions,  that  without  this  distinc 
tion  metaphysics  is  absolutely  impossible,  or  is  at 
best  a  random,  bungling  attempt  to  build  a  castle  in 
the  air  without  a  knowledge  of  the  materials  or  of 
their  fitness  for  any  purpose.  Had  the  Critique  of 
Pure  Reason  done  nothing  but  first  point  out  this  dis 
tinction,  it  had  thereby  contributed  more  to  clear  up 
our  conception  of,  and  to  guide  our  inquiry  in,  the 
field  of  metaphysics,  than  all  the  vain  efforts  which 
have  hitherto  been  made  to  satisfy  the  transcendent 
problems  of  pure  reason,  without  ever  surmising  that 
we  were  in  quite  another  field  than  that  of  the  under 
standing,  and  hence  classing  concepts  of  the  under 
standing  and  those  of  reason  together,  as  if  they 
were  of  the  same  kind. 

§  42.  All  pure  cognitions  of  the  understanding 
have  this  feature,  that  their  concepts  present  them 
selves  in  experience,  and  their  principles  can  be  con 
firmed  by  it ;  whereas  the  transcendent  cognitions  of 


94  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

reason  cannot,  either  as  ideas,  appear  in  experience, 
or  as  propositions  ever  be  confirmed  or  refuted  by  it. 
Hence  whatever  errors  may  slip  in  unawares,  can  only 
be  discovered  by  pure  reason  itself — a  discovery  of 
much  difficulty,  because  this  very  reason  naturally 
becomes  dialectical  by  means  of  its  ideas,  and  this 
unavoidable  illusion  cannot  be  limited  by  any  objec 
tive  and  dogmatical  researches  into  things,  but  by  a 
subjective  investigation  of  reason  itself  as  a  source  of 
ideas. 

§  43.  In  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  it  was  always 
my  greatest  care  to  endeavor  not  only  carefully  to  dis 
tinguish  the  several  species  of  cognition,  but  to  de 
rive  concepts  belonging  to  each  one  of  them  from 
their  common  source.  I  did  this  in  order  that  by 
knowing  whence  they  originated,  I  might  determine 
their  use  with  safety,  and  also  have  the  unanticipated 
but  invaluable  advantage  of  knowing  the  completeness 
of  my  enumeration,  classification  and  specification  of 
concepts  a  priori,  and  therefore  according  to  prin 
ciples.  Without  this,  metaphysics  is  mere  rhapsody, 
in  which  no  one  knows  whether  he  has  enough,  or 
whether  and  where  something  is  still  wanting.  We 
can  indeed  have  this  advantage  only  in  pure  philos 
ophy,  but  of  this  philosophy  it  constitutes  the  very 
essence. 

As  I  had  found  the  origin  of  the  categories  in  the 
four  logical  functions  of  all  the  judgments  of  the  un 
derstanding,  it  was  quite  natural  to  seek  the  origin  of 
the  ideas  in  the  three  functions  of  the  syllogisms  of 
reason.  For  as  soon  as  these  pure  concepts  of  rea 
son  (the  transcendental  ideas)  are  given,  they  could 
hardly,  except  they  be  held  innate,  be  found  anywhere 
else,  than  in  the  same  activity  of  reason,  which,  so 


HOW  IS   METAPHYSICS   IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?  95 

far  as  it  regards  mere  form,  constitutes  the  logical 
element  cf  the  syllogisms  of  reason ;  but,  so  far  as  it 
represents  judgments  of  the  understanding  with  re 
spect  to  the  one  or  to  the  other  form  a  priori,  consti 
tutes  transcendental  concepts  of  pure  reason. 

The  formal  distinction  of  syllogisms  renders  their 
division  into  categorical,  hypothetical,  and  disjunc 
tive  necessary.  The'  concepts  of  reason  founded  on 
them  contained  therefore,  rfirst,  the  idea  of  the  com 
plete  subject  (the  substantial);  secondly,  the  idea  of 
the  complete  series  of  conditions;  thirdly,  the  deter 
mination  of  all  concepts  in  the  idea  of  a  complete 
complex  of  that  which  is  possible.1  The  first  idea  is 
psychological,  the  second  cosmological,  the  third 
theological,  and,  as  all  three  give  occasion  to  Dialec 
tics,  yet  each  in  its  own  way,  the  division  of  the 
whole  Dialects  of  pure  reason  into  its  Paralogism,  its 
Antinomy,  and  its  Ideal,  was  arranged  accordingly. 
Through  this  deduction  we  may  feel  assured  that  all 
the  claims  of  pure  reason  are  completely  represented, 
and  that  none  can  be  wanting ;  because  the  faculty  of 
reason  itself,  whence  they  all  take  their  origin,  is 
thereby  completely  surveyed. 

§  44.  In  these  general  considerations  it  is  also  re 
markable  that  the  ideas  of  reason  are  unlike  the  cate 
gories,  of  no  service  to  the  use  of  our  understanding 

lln  disjunctive  judgments  \ve  consider  all  possibility  as  divided  in  re 
spect  to  a  particular  concept.  By  the  ontological  principle  of  the  universal 
determination  of  a  thing  in  general,  I  understand  the  principle  that  either 
the  one  or  the  other  of  all  possible  contradictory  predicates  must  be  assigned 
to  any  object.  This  is  at  the  same  time  the  principle  of  all  disjunctive  judg 
ments,  constituting  the  foundation  of  our  conception  of  possibility,  and  in  it 
the  possibility  of  every  object  in  general  is  considered  as  determined.  This 
may  serve  as  a  slight  explanation  of  the  above  proposition  :  that  the  activity 
of  reason  in  disjunctive  syllogisms  is  formally  the  same  as  that  by  which  it 
fashions  the  idea  of  a  universal  conception  of  all  reality,  containing  in  itself 
that  which  is  positive  in  all  contradictory  predicates. 


96  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

in  experience,  but  quite  dispensable,  and  become  even 
an  impediment  to  the  maxims  of  a  rational  cognition 
of  nature.  Yet  in  another  aspect  still  to  be  determined 
they  are  necessary.  Whether  the  soul  is  or  is  not  a 
simple  substance,  is  of  no  consequence  to  us  in  the 
explanation  of  its  phenomena.  For  we  cannot  render 
the  notion  of  a  simple  being  intelligible  by  any  pos 
sible  experience  that  is  sensuous  or  concrete.  The 
notion  is  therefore  quite  void  as  regards  all  hoped-for 
insight  into  the  cause  of  phenomena,  and  cannot  at 
all  serve  as  a  principle  of  the  explanation  of  that 
which  internal  or  external  experience  supplies.  So 
the  cosmological  ideas  of  the  beginning  of  the  world 
or  of  its  eternity  (a  parte  ante}  cannot  be  of  any  greater 
service  to  us  for  the  explanation  of  any  event  in  the 
world  itself.  And  finally  we  must,  according  to  a 
right  maxim  of  the  philosophy  of  nature,  refrain  from 
all  explanations  of  the  design  of  nature,  drawn  from 
the  will  of  a  Supreme  Being  ;  because  this  would  not 
be  natural  philosophy,  but  an  acknowledgment  that 
we  have  come  to  the  end  of  it.  The  use  of  these 
ideas,  therefore,  is  quite  different  from  that  of  those 
categories  by  which  (and  by  the  principles  built  upon 
which)  experience  itself  first  becomes  possible.  But 
our  laborious  analytics  of  the  understanding  would  be 
superfluous  if  we  had  nothing  else  in  view  than  the 
mere  cognition  of  nature  as  it  can  be  given  in  experi 
ence ;  for  reason  does  its  work,  both  in  mathematics 
and  in  the  science  of  nature,  quite  safely  and  well 
without  any  of  this  subtle  deduction.  Therefore  our 
Critique  of  the  Understanding  combines  with  the  ideas 
of  pure  reason  for  a  purpose  which  lies  beyond  the 
empirical  use  of  the  understanding  ;  but  this  we  have 
above  declared  to  be  in  this  aspect  totally  inadmis- 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?  97 

sible,  and  without  any  object  or  meaning.  Yet  there 
must  be  a  harmony  between  that  of  the  nature  of  rea 
son  and  that  of  the  understanding,  and  the  former 
must  contribute  to  the  perfection  of  the  latter,  and 
cannot  possibly  upset  it. 

The  solution  of  this  question  is  as  follows  :  Pure 
reason  does  not  in  its  ideas  point  to  particular  ob 
jects,  which  lie  beyond  the  field  of  experience,  but 
only  requires  completeness  of  the  use  of  the  under 
standing  in  the  system  of  experience.  But  this  com 
pleteness  can  be  a  completeness  of  principles  only, 
not  of  intuitions  (i.  e.,  concrete  atsights  or  Anschau- 
ungen)  and  of  objects.  In  order  however  to  represent 
the  ideas  definitely,  reason  conceives  them  after  the 
fashion  of  the  cognition  of  an  object.  The  cognition 
is  as  far  as  these  rules  are  concerned  completely  de 
termined,  but  the  object  is  only  an  idea  invented  for 
the  purpose  of  bringing  the  cognition  of  the  under 
standing  as  near  as  possible  to  the  completeness  rep 
resented  by  that  idea. 

Prefatory  Remark  to  the  Dialectics  of  Pure  Reason. 

§  45.  We  have  above  shown  in  §§  33  and  34  that 
the  purity  of  the  categories  from  all  admixture  of  sen 
suous  determinations  may  mislead  reason  into  extend 
ing  their  use,  quite  beyond  all  experience,  to  things 
in  themselves;  though  as  these  categories  themselves 
find  no  intuition  which  can  give  them  meaning  or 
sense  in  concrete,  they,  as  mere  logical  functions,  can 
represent  a  thing  in  general,  but  not  give  by  them 
selves  alone  a  determinate  concept  of  anything.  Such 
hyperbolical  objects  are  distinguised  by  the  appella 
tion  of  Noumena,  or  pure  beings  of  the  understanding 
(or  better,  beings  of  thought),  such  as,  for  example, 


98  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

" substance, "  but  conceived  without  permanence  in 
tune,  or  "cause/1  but  not  acting  in  time,  etc.  Here 
predicates,  that  only  serve  to  make  the  conformity-to- 
law  of  experience  possible,  are  applied  to  these  con 
cepts,  and  yet  they  are  deprived  of  all  the  conditions 
of  intuition,  on  which  alone  experience  is  possible, 
and  so  these  concepts  lose  all  significance. 

There  is  no  danger,  however,  of  the  understanding 
spontaneously  making  an  excursion  so  very  wantonly 
beyond  its  own  bounds  into  the  field  of  the  mere  crea 
tures  of  thought,  without  being  impelled  by  foreign 
laws.  But  when  reason,  which  cannot  be  fully  satis 
fied  with  any  empirical  use  of  the  rules  of  the  under 
standing,  as  being  always  conditioned,  requires  a  com 
pletion  of  this  chain  of  conditions,  then  the  under 
standing  is  forced  out  of  its  sphere.  And  then  it  partly 
represents  objects  of  experience  in  a  series  so  extended 
that  no  experience  can  grasp,  partly  even  (with  a  view 
to  complete  the  series)  it  seeks  entirely  beyond  it 
noumena,  to  which  it  can  attach  that  chain,  and  so, 
having  at  last  escaped  from  the  conditions  of  experi 
ence,  make  its  attitude  as  it  were  final.  These  are 
then  the  transcendental  ideas,  which,  though  accord 
ing  to  the  true  but  hidden  ends  of  the  natural  deter 
mination  of  our  reason,  they  may  aim  not  at  extrava 
gant  concepts,  but  at  an  unbounded  extension  of  their 
empirical  use,  yet  seduce  the  understanding  by  an 
unavoidable  illusion  to  a  transcendent  use,  which, 
though  deceitful,  cannot  be  restrained  within  the 
bounds  of  experience  by  any  resolution,  but  only  by 
scientific  instruction  and  with  much  difficulty. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?  99 

.  I.    The  Psychological  Idea. 1    ^f 

§  46.  People  have  long  since  observed,  that  in  all 
substances  the  proper  subject,  that  which  remains 
after  all  the  accidents  (as  predicates)  are  abstracted, 
consequently  that  which  forms  the  substance  of  things 
remains  unknown,  and  various  complaints  have  been 
made  concerning  these  limits  to  our  knowledge.  But 
it  will  be  well  to  consider  that  the  human  understand 
ing  is  not  to  be  blamed  for  its  inability  to  know  the 
substance  of  things,  that  is,  to  determine  it  by  itself, 
but  rather  for  requiring  to  cognise  it  which  is  a  mere 
idea  definitely  as  though  it  were  a  given  object.  Pure 
reason  requires  us  to  seek  for  every  predicate  of  a 
thing  its  proper  subject,  and  for  this  subject,  which 
is  itself  necessarily  nothing  but  a  predicate,  its  sub 
ject,  and  so  on  indefinitely  (or  as  far  as  we  can  reach). 
But  hence  it  follows,  that  we  must  not  hold  anything, 
at  which  we  can  arrive^  to  .be  an  ultimate  subject, 
and  that  substance  itself  never  cjm_b^J^qught_  by  jour 
understandinjk_however  deep  we  may  penetrate,  even 
if  all  nature  were  iin veiled  tp_us.  For  the  specific 
nature  of  our  umlerstaii'.lin;-;'  consists  in  thinkiiii;  every 
thing  discursively,  that  is,  representing  it  by  concepts, 
and  so  by  mere  predicates,  to  which  therefore  the  ab 
solute  subject  must  always  be  wanting.  Hence  all 
the  real  properties,  by  which  we  cognise  bodies,  are 
mere  accidents,  not  excepting  impenetrability,  which 
we  can  only  represent  to  ourselves  as  the  effect  of  a 
power  of  which  the  subject  is  unknown  to  us. 

Now  we  appear  to  have  this  substance  in  the  con 
sciousness  of  ourselves  (in  the  thinking  subject),  and 
indeed  in  an  immediate  intuition;  for  all  the  predi- 

1  See  Critique  of  Pure  Reason,   lron  den  Paralogismen  der  reinen  Vernunfl. 


100  KANT  S  PROLEGOMENA. 

cates  of  an  internal  sense  refer  to  the  ego,  as  a  sub 
ject,  and  I  cannot  conceive  myself  as  the  predicate  of 
any  other  subject.  Hence  completeness  in  the  refer 
ence  of  the  given  concepts  as  predicates  to  a  subject 
— not  merely  an  idea,  but  an  object — that  is,  the  ab 
solute  subject  itself,  seems  to  be  given  in  experience. 
But  this  expectation  is  disappointed.  For  the  ego  is 
not  a  concept,1  but  only  the  indication  of  the  object 
of  the  internal  sense,  so  far  as  we  cognise  it  by  no 
further  predicate.  Consequently  it  cannot  be  in  itself 
a  predicate  of  any  other  thing;  but  just  as  little  can 
it  be  a  determinate  concept  of  an  absolute  subject, 
but  is,  as  in  all  other  cases,  only  the  reference  of  the 
internal  phenomena  to  their  unknown  subject.  Yet 
this  idea  (which  serves  very  well,  as  a  regulative  prin 
ciple,  totally  to  destroy  all  materialistic  explanations 
of  the  internal  phenomena  of  the  soul)  occasions  by  a 
very  natural  misunderstanding  a  very  specious  argu 
ment,  which,  from  this  supposed  cognition  of  the 
substance  of  our  thinking  being,  infers  its  nature,  so 
far  as  the  knowledge  of  it  falls  quite  without  the  com 
plex  of  experience. 

§  47.  But  though  we  may  call  this  thinking  self 
(the  soul)  substance,  as  being  the  ultimate  subject  of 
thinking  which  cannot  be  further  represented  as  the 
predicate  of  another  thing;  it  remains  quite  empty 
and  without  significance,  if  permanence — the  quality 
which  renders  the  concept  of  substances  in  experience 
fruitful — cannot  be  proved  of  it. 

But  permanence  can  never  be  proved  of   the  con- 

1  Were  the  representation  of  the  apperception  (the  Ego)  a  concept,  by 
which  anything  could  be  thought,  it  could  be  used  as  a  predicate  of  other 
things  or  contain  predicates  in  itself.  But  it  is  nothing  more  than  the  feeling 
of  an  existence  without  tbf  Inn^t  definite  conception  and  is  only  the  repre 
sentation  of  that  to  which  ;-\\  think  ing  stands  in  relation  (relatione  accidttitis}. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         IOI 

cept  of  a  substance,  as  a  thing  in  itself,  but  for  the 
purposes  of  experience  only.  This  is  sufficiently 
shown  by  the  first  Analogy  of  Experience,1  and  who 
ever  will  not  yield  to  this  proof  may  try  for  himself 
whether  he  can  succeed  in  proving,  from  the  concept 
of  a  subject  which  does  not  exist  itself  as  the  predi 
cate  of  another  thing,  that  its  existence  is  thoroughly 
permanent,  and  that  it  cannot  either  in  itself  cr  by 
any  natural  cause  originate  or  be  annihilated.  These 
synthetical  a  priori  propositions  can  never  be  proved 
in  themselves,  but  only  in  reference  to  things  as  ob 
jects  of  possible  experience. 

§  48.  If  therefore  from  the  concept  of  the  soul  as 
a  substance,  we  would  infer  its  permanence,  this  can 
hold  good  as  regards  possible  experience  only,  not 
[of  the  soul]  as  a  thing  in  itself  and  beyond  all  pos 
sible  experience.  But  life  is  the  subjective  condition 
of  all  our  possible  experience,  consequently  we  can 
only  infer  the  permanence  of  the  soul  in  life ;  for  the 
death  of  man  is  the  end  of  all  experience  which  con 
cerns  the  soul  as  an  object  of  experience,  except  the 
contrary  be  proved,  which  is  the  very  question  in 
hand.  The  permanence  of  the  soul  can  therefore 
only  be  proved  (and  no  one  cares  for  that)  during  the 
life  of  man,  but  not,  as  we  desire  to  do,  after  death ; 
and  for  this  general  reason,  that  the  concept  of  sub 
stance,  so  far  as  it  is  to  be  considered  necessarily 
combined  with  the  concept  of  permanence,  can  be  so 
combined  only  according  to  the  principles  of  possible 
experience,  and  therefore  for  the  purposes  of  experi 
ence  only.2 

1  Cf.  Critique,  Von  den  Analogien  tier  Erfahrung. 

2  It  is  indeed  very  remarkable  how  carelessly  metaphysicians  have  always 
passed   over  the  principle  of  the  permanence  of  substances  without  ever 


IO2  KAN1S  PROLEGOMENA. 

§'49.  That  there  is  something  real  without  us 
which  not  only  corresponds,  but  must  correspond,  to 
our  external  perceptions,  can  likewise  be  proved  to 
be  not  a  connexion  of  things  in  themselves,  but  for 
the  sake  of  experience.  This  means  that  there  is 
something  empirical,  i.  e. ,  some  phenomenon  in  space 
without  us,  that  admits  of  a  satisfactory  proof,  for  we 
have  nothing  to  do  with  other  objects  than  those 
which  belong  to  possible  experience;  because  objects 
which  cannot  be  given  us  in  any  experience,  do  not 
exist  for  us.  Empirically  without  me  is  that  which 
appears  in  space,  and  space,  together  with  all  the 
phenomena  which  it  contains,  belongs  to  the  represen 
tations,  whose  connexion  according  to  laws  of  experi 
ence  proves  their  objective  truth,  just  as  the  connexion 
of  the  phenomena  of  the  internal  sense  proves  the  ac 
tuality  of  my  soul  (as  an  object  of  the  internal  sense). 
By  means  of  external  experience  I  am  conscious  of 
the  actuality  of  bodies,  as  external  phenomena  in 
space,  in  the  same  manner  as  by  means  of  the  inter 
nal  experience  I  am  conscious  of  the  existence  of  my 

attempting  a  proof  of  it;  doubtless  because  they  found  themselves  aban 
doned  by  all  proofs  as  soon  as  they  began  to  deal  with  the  concept  of  sub 
stance.  Common  sense,  which  felt  distinctly  that  without  this  presupposition 
no  union  of  perceptions  in  experience  is  possible,  supplied  the  want  by  a 
postulate.  From  experience  itself  it  never  could  derive  such  a  principle, 
parily  because  substances  cannot  be  so  traced  in  all  their  alterations  and 
dissolutions,  that  the  matter  can  always  be  found  undiminishod.  partly  be 
cause  the  principle  contains  necessity,  which  is  always  the  sign  of  an  a  priori 
principle.  People  then  boldly  applied  this  postulate  to  the  concept  of  soul 
as  a  substance,  and  concluded  a  necessary  continuance  of  the  soul  after  the 
death  of  man  (especially  as  the  simplicity  of  this  substance,  which  is  interred 
from  the  indivisibility  of  consciousness,  secured  it  from  destruction  by  dis 
solution).  Had  they  found  the  genuine  source  of  this  principle — a  discovery 
which  requires  deeper  researches  than  they  were  ever  inclined  to  make — 
they  would  have  seen,  that  the  law  of  the  permanence  of  substances  has 
place  for  the  purposes  of  experience  only,  and  hence  can  hold  good  of  things 
so  far  as  they  are  to  be  cognised  and  conjoined  with  others  in  experience, 
but  never  independently  of  all  possible  experience,  and  consequently  cannot 
hold  good  of  the  soul  after  death. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?        103 

soul  in  time,  but  this  soul  is  only  cognised  as  an  ob 
ject  of  the  internal  sense  by  phenomena  that  consti- 
tute  an  internal  state,  and  of  which  the  essence  in  it 
self,  which  forms  the  basis  of  these  phenomena,  is 
unknown.  Cartesian  idealism  therefore  does  nothing 
but  distinguish  external  experience  from  dreaming; 
and  the  conformity  to  law  (as  a  criterion  of  its  truth) 
of  the  former,  from  the  irregularity  and  the  false  illu 
sion  of  the  latter.  In  both  it  presupposes  space  and 
time  as  conditions  of  the  existence  of  objects,  and  it 
only  inquires  whether  the  objects  of  the  external 
senses,  which  we  when  awake  put  in  space,  are  as 
actually  to  be  found  in  it,  as  the  object  of  the  internal 
sense,  the  soul,  is  in  time  ;  that  is,  whether  experience 
carries  with  it  sure  criteria  to  distinguish  it  from  im 
agination.  This  doubt,  however,  may  easily  be  dis 
posed  of,  and  we  always  do  so  in  common  life  by  in 
vestigating  the  connexion  of  phenomena  in  both  space 
and  time  according  to  universal  laws  of  experience, 
and  we  cannot  doubt,  when  the  representation  of  ex 
ternal  things  throughout  agrees  therewith,  that  they 
constitute  truthful  experience.  Material  idealism,  in 
which  phenomena  are  considered  as  such  only  accord 
ing  to  their  connexion  in  experience,  may  accordingly 
be  very  easily  refuted;  and  it  is  just  as  sure  an  expe 
rience,  that  bodies  exist  without  us  (in  space),  as  that 
I  myself  exist  according  to  the  representation  of  the 
internal  sense  (in  time)  :  for  the  notion  without  us, 
only  signifies  existence  in  space.  However  as  the 
Ego  in  the  proposition,  "I  am,"  means  not  only  the 
object  of  internal  intuition  (in  time),  but  the  subject 
of  consciousness,  just  as  body  means  not  only  external 
intuition  (in  space),  but  the  thing-in-itself,  which  is 
the  basis  of  this  phenomenon  ;  [as  this  is  the  case] 


104  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

the  question,  whether  bodies  (as  phenomena  of  the 
external  sense)  exist  as  bodies  apart  from  my  thoughts, 
may  without  any  hesitation  be  denied  in  nature.  But 
the  question,  whether  I  myself  as  a  phenomenon  of 
the  internal  sense  (the  soul  according  to  empirical 
psychology)  exist  apart  from  my  faculty  of  represen 
tation  in  time,  is  an  exactly  similar  inquiry,  and  must 
likewise  be  answered  in  the  negative.  And  in  this 
manner  everything,  when  it  is  reduced  to  its  true 
meaning,  is  decided  and  certain.  The  formal  (which 
I  have  also  called  transcendental)  actually  abolishes 
the  material,  or  Cartesian,  idealism.  For  if  space  be 
nothing  but  a  form  of  my  sensibility,  it  is  as  a  repre 
sentation  in  me  just  as  actual  as  I  myself  am,  and 
nothing  but  the  empirical  truth  of  the  representations 
in  it  remains  for  consideration.  But,  if  this  is  not  the 
case,  if  space  and  the  phenomena  in  it  are  something 
existing  without  us,  then  all  the  criteria  of  experience 
beyond  our  perception  can  never  prove  the  actuality 
of  these  objects  without  us. 

II.    The  Cosmo  logical  Id  fa.1 

§  50.  This  product  of  pure  reason  in  its  tran 
scendent  use  is  its  most  remarkable  curiosity.  It 
serves  as  a  very  powerful  agent  to  rouse  philosophy 
from  its  dogmatic  slumber,  and  to  stimulate  it  to  the 
arduous  task  of  undertaking  a  Critique  of  Reason  itself. 

I  term  this  idea  cosmological,  because  it  always 
takes  its  object  only  from  the  sensible  world,  and  does 
not  use  any  other  than  those  whose  object  is  given  to 
sense,  consequently  it  remains  in  this  respect  in  its 
native  home,  it  does  not  become  transcendent,  and  is 
therefore  so  far  not  mere  idea ;  whereas,  to  conceive 

ICf.  Critique,  Die  Antinomic  der  reinen  Vernunft. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         IO5 

the  soul  as  a  sirfiple  substance,  already  means  to  con 
ceive  such  an  object  (the  simple)  as  cannot  be  pre 
sented  to  the  senses.  Yet  the  cosmological  idea 
extends  the  connexion  of  the  conditioned  with  its  con 
dition  (whether  the  connexion  is  mathematical  or  dy 
namical)  so  far,  that  experience  never  can  keep  up 
with  it.  It  is  therefore  with  regard  to  this  point  always 
an  idea,  whose  object  never  can  be  adequately  given 
in  any  experience. 

§  51.  In  the  first  place,  the  use  of  a  system  of 
categories  becomes  here  so  obvious  and  unmistakable, 
that  even  if  there  were  not  several  other  proofs  of  it, 
this  alone  would  sufficiently  prove  it  indispensable  in 
the  system  of  pure  reason.  There  are  only  four  such 
transcendent  ideas,  as  there  are  so  many  classes  of 
categories ;  in  each  of  which,  however,  they  refer  only 
to  the  absolute  completeness  of  the  series  of  the  con 
ditions  for  a  given  conditioned.  In  analogy  to  these 
cosmological  ideas  there  are  only  four  kinds  of  dia 
lectical  assertions  of  pure  reason,  which,  as  they  are 
dialectical,  thereby  prove,  that  to  each  of  them,  oil 
equally  specious  principles  of  pure  reason,  a  contra 
dictory  assertion  stands  opposed.  As  all  the  meta 
physical  art  of  the  most  subtile  distinction  cannot 
prevent  this  opposition,  it  compels  the  philosopher 
to  recur  to  the  first  sources  of  pure  reason  itself.  This 
Antinomy,  not  arbitrarily  invented,  but  founded  in 
the  nature  of  human  reason,  and  hence  unavoidable 
and  never  ceasing,  contains  the  following  four  theses 
together  with  their  antitheses: 

i. 

Thesis. 
The  World  has,  as  to  Time  and  Space,  a  Beginning  (limit). 


Io6  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

Antithesis. 
The  World  is,  as  to  Time  and  Space,  infinite. 

2. 

Thesis. 
Everything  in  the  World  consists  of  [elements  that  are]  simple. 

Antithesis. 
There  is  nothing  simple,  but  everything  is  composite. 

3- 

Thesis. 
There  are  in  the  World  Causes  through  Freedom. 

Antithesis. 
There  is  no  Liberty,  but  all  is  Nature. 

4- 

Thesis. 
In  the  Series  of  the  World-Causes  there  is  some  necessary  Being. 

Antithesis. 

There  is  Nothing  necessary  in  the  World,  but  in  this  Series  All  is 
incidental. 

§  52.  a.  Here  is  the  most  singular  phenomenon  of 
human  reason,  no  other  instance  of  which  can  be 
shown  in  any  other  use.  If  we,  as  is  commonly  done, 
represent  to  ourselves  the  appearances  of  the  sensible 
world  as  things  in  themselves,  if  we  assume  the  prin 
ciples  of  their  combination  as  principles  universally 
valid  of  things  in  themselves  and  not  merely  of  expe 
rience,  as  is  usually,  nay  without  our  Critique,  un 
avoidably  done,  there  arises  an  unexpected  conflict, 
which  never  can  be  removed  in  the  common  dogmat 
ical  way ;  because  the  thesis,  as  well  as  the  antithesis, 
can  be  shown  by  equally  clear,  evident,  and  irresist- 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?        IC>7 

ible  proofs — for  I  pledge  myself  as  to  the  correctness 
of  all  these  proofs — and  reason  therefore  perceives 
that  it  is  divided  with  itself,  a  state  at  which  the  scep 
tic  rejoices,  but  which  must  make  the  critical  philos 
opher  pause  and  feel  ill  at  ease. 

§  52.  b.  We  may  blunder  in  various  ways  in  meta 
physics  without  any  fear  of  being  detected  in  false 
hood.  For  we  never  can  be  refuted  by  experience  if 
we  but  avoid  self-contradiction,  which  in  synthetical, 
though  purely  fictitious  propositions,  may  be  done 
whenever  the  concepts,  which  we  connect,  are  mere 
ideas,  that  cannot  be  given  (in  their  whole  content) 
in  experience.  For  how  can  we  make  out  by  experi 
ence,  whether  the  world  is  from  eternity  or  had  a  be 
ginning,  whether  matter  is  infinitely  divisible  or  con 
sists  of  simple  parts?  Such  concept  cannot  be  given 
in  any  experience,  be  it  ever  so  extensive,  and  conse 
quently  the  falsehood  either  of  the  positive  or  the 
negative  proposition  cannot  be  discovered  by  this 
touch-stone. 

The  only  possible  way  in  which  reason  could  have 
revealed  unintentionally  its  secret  Dialectics,  falsely 
announced  as  Dogmatics,  would  be  when  it  were  made 
to  ground  an  assertion  upon  a  universally  admitted 
principle,  and  to  deduce  the  exact  contrary  with  the 
greatest  accuracy  of  inference  from  another  which  is 
equally  granted.  This  is  actually  here  the  case  with 
regard  to  four  natural  ide-as  of  reason,  whence  four 
assertions  on  the  one  side,  and  as  many  counter-asser 
tions  on  the  other  arise,  each  consistently  following 
from  universally-acknowledged  principles.  Thus  they 
reveal  by  the  use  of  these  principles  the  dialectical 
illusion  of  pure  reason  which  would  otherwise  for 
ever  remain  concealed. 


io8  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA.   . 

This  is  therefore  a  decisive  experiment,  which 
must  necessarily  expose  any  error  lying  hidden  in  the 
assumptions  of  reason.1  Contradictory  propositions 
cannot  both  be  false,  except  the  concept,  which  is  the 
subject  of  both,  is  self-contradictory;  for  example, 
the  propositions,  "a  square  circle  is  round,  and  a 
square  circle  is  not  round,"  are  both  false.  For,  as 
to  the  former  it  is  false,  that  the  circle  is  round,  be 
cause  it  is  quadrangular;  and  it  is  likewise  false,  that 
it  is  not  round,  that  is,  angular,  because  it  is  a  circle. 
For  the  logical  criterion  of  the  impossibility  of  a  con 
cept  consists  in  this,  that  if  we  presuppose  it,  two 
contradictory  propositions  both  become  false ;  conse 
quently,  as  no  middle  between  them  is  conceivable, 
nothing  at  all  is  thought  by  that  concept. 

§  52.  c.  The  first  two  antinomies,  which  I  call 
mathematical,  because  they  are  concerned  with  the 
addition  or  division  of  the  homogeneous,  are  founded 
on  such  a  self-contradictory  concept ;  and  hence  I  ex 
plain  how  it  happens,  that  both  the  Thesis  and  Anti 
thesis  of  the  two  are  false. 

When  I  speak  of  objects  in  time  and  in  space,  it  is 
not  of  things  in  themselves,  of  which  I  know  nothing, 
but  of  things  in  appearance,  that  is,  of  experience, 
as  the  particular  way  of  cognising  objects  which  is 
afforded  to  man.  I  must  not  say  of  what  I  think  in 
time  or  in  space,  that  in  itself,  and  independent  of 

1  I  therefore  would  be  pleased  to  have  the  critical  reader  to  devote  to  this 
antinomy  of  pure  reason  his  chief  attention,  because  nature  itself  seems  to 
have  established  it  with  a  view  to  stagger  reason  in  its  daring  pretentions, 
and  to  force  it  to  self-examination.  For  every  proof,  which  I  have  given,  as 
well  of  the  thesis  as  of  the  antithesis,  I  undertake  to  be  responsible,  and 
thereby  to  show  the  certainty  of  the  inevitable  antinomy  of  reason.  When 
the  reader  is  brought  by  this  curious  phenomenon  to  fall  back  upon  the  proof 
of  the  presumption  upon  which  it  rests,  he  will  feel  himself  obliged  to  in 
vestigate  the  ultimate  foundation  of  all  the  cognition  of  pure  reason  with  me 
more  thoroughly. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?        IOQ 

these  my  thoughts,  it  exists  in  space  and  in  time;  for 
in  that  case  I  should  contradict  myself;  because  space 
and  time,  together  with  the  appearances  in  them,  are 
nothing  existing  in  themselves  and  outside  of  my  rep 
resentations,  but  are  themselves  only  modes  of  repre 
sentation,  and  it  is  palpably  contradictory  to  say,  that 
a  mere  mode  of  representation  exists  without  our  rep 
resentation.  Objects  of  the  senses  therefore  exist  only 
in  experience;  whereas  to  give  them  a  self-subsisting 
existence  apart  from  experience  or  before  it,  is  merely 
to  represent  to  ourselves  that  experience  actually  ex 
ists  apart  from  experience  or  before  it. 

Now  if  I  inquire  after  the  quantity  of  the  world,  as 
to  space  and  time,  it  is  equally  impossible,  as  regards 
all  my  notions,  to  declare  it  infinite  or  to  declare  it 
finite.  For  neither  assertion  can  be  contained  in  expe 
rience,  because  experience  either  of  an  infinite  space, 
or  of  an  infinite  time  elapsed,  or  again,  of  the  bound 
ary  of  the  world  by  a  void  space,  or  by  an  antecedent 
void  time,  is  impossible;  these  are  mere  ideas.  This 
quantity  of  the  world,  which  is  determined  in  either 
way,  should  therefore  exist  in  the  world  itself  apart 
from  all  experience.  This  contradicts  the  notion  of  a 
world  of  sense,  which  is  merely  a  complex  of  the  ap 
pearances  whose  existence  and  connexion  occur  only 
in  our  representations,  that  is,  in  experience,  since  this 
latter  is  not  an  object  in  itself,  but  a  mere  mode  of 
representation.  Hence  it  follows,  that  as  the  concept 
of  an  absolutely  existing  world  of  sense  is  self-contra 
dictory,  the  solution  of  the  problem  concerning  its 
quantity,  whether  attempted  affirmatively  or  nega 
tively,  is  always  false. 

The  same  holds  good  of  the  second  antinomy, 
which  relates  to  the  division  of  phenomena.  For  these 


no  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

are  mere  representations,  and  the  parts  exist  merely 
in  their  representation,  consequently  in  the  division, 
or  in  a  possible  experience  where  they  are  given,  and 
the  division  reaches  only  as  far  as  this  latter  reaches. 
To  assume  that  an  appearance,  e.  g.,  that  of  body, 
contains  in  itself  before  all  experience  all  the  parts, 
which  any  possible  experience  can  ever  reach,  is  to 
impute  to  a  mere  appearance,  which  can  exist  only  in 
experience,  an  existence  previous  to  experience.  In 
other  words,  it  would  mean  that  mere  representations 
exist  before  they  can  be  found  in  our  faculty  of  repre 
sentation.  Such  an  assertion  is  self-contradictory,  as 
also  every  solution  of  our  misunderstood  problem, 
whether  we  maintain,  that  bodies  in  themselves  con 
sist  of  an  infinite  number  of  parts,  or  of  a  finite  num 
ber  of  simple  parts. 

§  53.  In  the  first  (the  mathematical)  class  of  anti 
nomies  the  falsehood  of  the  assumption  consists  in 
representing  in  one  concept  something  self  contra- 
dictory  as  if  it  were  compatible  (i.  e.,  an  appearance 
as  an  object  in  itself).  But,  as  to  the  second  (the  dy 
namical)  class  of  antinomies,  the  falsehood  of  the  rep 
resentation  consists  in  representing  as  contradictory 
what  is  compatible  ;  so  that,  as  in  the  former  case, 
the  opposed  assertions  are  both  false,  in  this  case,  on 
the  other  hand,  where  they  are  opposed  to  one  an 
other  by  mere  misunderstanding,  they  may  both  be 
true. 

Any  mathematical  connexion  necessarily  presup 
poses  homogeneity  of  what  is  connected  (in  the  con 
cept  of  magnitude),  while  the  dynamical  one  by  nr» 
means  requires  the  same.  When  we  have  to  deal  with 
extended  magnitudes,  all  the  parts  must  be  homogene 
ous  with  one  another  and  with  the  whole ;  whereas, 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?        Ill 

in  the  connexion  of  cause  and  effect,  homogeneity 
may  indeed  likewise  be  found,  but  is  not  necessary; 
for  the  concept  of  causality  (by  means  of  which  some- 
tiling  is  posited  through  something  else  quite  different 
from  it),  at  all  events,  does  not  require  it. 

If  the  objects  of  the  world  of  sense  are  taken  for 
things  in  themselves,  and  the  above  laws  of  nature 
for  the  laws  of  things  in  themselves,  the  contradiction 
would  be  unavoidable.  So  also,  if  the  subject  of  free 
dom  were,  like  other  objects,  represented  as  mere  ap 
pearance,  the  contradiction  would  be  just  as  unavoid 
able,  for  the  same  predicate  would  at  once  be  affirmed 
and  denied  of  the  same  kind  of  object  in  the  same 
sense.  But  if  natural  necessity  is  referred  merely  to 
appearances,  and  freedom  merely  to  things  in  them 
selves,  no  contradiction  arises,  if  we  at  once  assume, 
or  admit  both  kinds  of  causality,  however  difficult  or 
impossible  it  may  be  to  make  the  latter  kind  conceiv 
able. 

As  appearance  every  effect  is  an  event,  or  some 
thing  that  happens  in  time ;  it  must,  according  to  the 
universal  law  of  nature,  be  preceded  by  a  determina 
tion  of  the  causality  of  its  cause  (a  state),  which  fol 
lows  according  to  a  constant  law.  But  this  determi 
nation  of  the  cause  as  causality  must  likewise  be 
something  that  takes  place  or  happens;  the  cause 
must  have  begun  to  act,  otherwise  no  succession  be 
tween  it  and  the  effect  could  be  conceived.  Other 
wise  the  effect,  as  well  as  the  causality  of  the  cause, 
would  have  always  existed.  Therefore  the  determi 
nation  of  the  cause  to  act  must  also  have  originated 
among  appearances,  and  must  consequently,  as  well 
as  its  effect,  be  an  event,  which  must  again  have  its 
cause,  and  so  on ;  hence  natural  necessity  must  be 


\ 


112  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

the  condition,  on  which  effective  causes  are  deter 
mined.  Whereas  if  freedom  is  to  be  a  property  of 
certain  causes  of  appearances,  it  must,  as  regards 
these,  which  are  events,  be  a  faculty  of  starting  them 
spontaneously,  that  is,  without  the  causality  of  the 
cause  itself,  and  hence  without  requiring  any  other 
ground  to  determine  its  start.  But  then  the  cause, 
as  to  its  causality,  must  not  rank  under  time-determi 
nations  of  its  state,  that  is,  it  cannot  be  an  appear 
ance,  and  must  be  considered  a  thing  in  itself,  while 
its  effects  would  be  only  appearances.1  If  without 
contradiction  we  can  think  of  the  beings  of  under 
standing  [Verstandesweseti}  as  exercising  such  an  in 
fluence  on  appearances,  then  natural  necessity  will 
attach  to  all  connexions  of  cause  and  effect  in  the 
sensuous  world,  though  on  the  other  hand,  freedom 
can  be  granted  to  such  cause,  as  is  itself  not  an  ap 
pearance  (but  the  foundation  of  appearance).  Nature 
therefore  and  freedom  can  without  contradiction  be 
attributed  to- the  very  same  thing,  but  in  different  re 
lations — on  one  side  as  a  phenomenon,  on  the  other 
as  a  thing  in  itself. 

We  have  in  us  a  faculty,  which  not  only  stands  in 

IThe  idea  of  freedom  occurs  only  in  the  relation  of  the  intellectual,  as 
cause,  to  the  appearance,  as  effect.  Hence  we  cannot  attribute  freedom  to 
matter  in  regard  to  the  incessant  action  by  which  it  fills  its  space,  though 
this  action  takes  place  from  an  internal  principle.  We  can  likewise  find  no 
notion  of  freedom  suitable  to  purely  rational  beings,  for  instance,  to  God,  so 
far  as  his  action  is  immanent.  For  his  action,  though  independent  of  ex 
ternal  determining  causes,  is  determined  in  his  eternal  reason,  that  is,  in  the 
divine  nature.  It  is  only,  if  something  is  to  start  by  an  action,  and  so  the 
effect  occurs  in  the  sequence  of  time,  or  in  the  world  of  sense  (e.  g.,  the  be 
ginning  of  the  world),  that  we  can  put  the  question,  whether  the  causality  of 
the  cause  must  in  its  turn  have  been  started,  or  whether  the  cause  can  origi 
nate  an  effect  without  its  causality  itself  beginning.  In  the  former  case  the 
concept  of  this  causality  is  a  concept  of  natural  necessity,  in  the  latter,  that 
of  freedom.  From  this  the  reader  will  see,  that,  as  1  explained  freedom  to 
be  the  faculty  of  starting  an  event  spontaneously,  I  have  exactly  hit  the  no 
^•01  which  is  the  prob;em  of  meta-physics. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         113 

connexion  with  its  subjective  determining  grounds 
that  are  the  natural  causes  of  its  actions,  and  is  so  far 
the  faculty  of  a  being  that  itself  belongs  to  appear 
ances,  but  is  also  referred  to  objective  grounds,  that 
are  only  ideas,  so  far  as  they  can  determine  this  fac 
ulty,  a  connexion  which  is  expressed  by  the  word 
ought.  This  faculty  is  called  reason,  and,  so  far  as 
we  consider  a  being  (man)  entirely  according  to  this 
objectively  determinable  reason,  he  cannot  be  consid 
ered  as  a  being  of  sense,  but  this  property  is  that  of  a 
thing  in  itself,  of  which  we  cannot  comprehend  the 
possibility — I  mean  how  the  ought  (which  however 
has  never  yet  taken  place)  should  determine  its  activ 
ity,  and  can  become  the  cause  of  actions,  whose  effect 
is  an  appearance  in  the  sensible  world.  Yet  the  cau 
sality  of  reason  would  be  freedom  with  regard  to  the 
effects  in  the  sensuous  world,  so  far  as  we  can  con 
sider  objective  grounds,  which  are  themselves  ideas, 
as  their  determinants.  For  its  action  in  that  case 
would  not  depend  upon  subjective  conditions,  conse 
quently  not  upon  those  of  time,  and  of  course  not 
upon  the  law  of  nature,  which  serves  to  determine 
them,  because  grounds  of  reason  give  to  actions  the 
rule  universally,  according  to  principles,  without  the 
influence  of  the  circumstances  of  either  time  or  place. 

What  I  adduce  here  is  merely  meant  as  an  ex 
ample  to  make  the  thing  intelligible,  and  does  not 
necessarily  belong  to  our  problem,  which  must  be  de 
cided  from  mere  concepts,  independently  of  the  prop 
erties  which  we  meet  in  the  actual  world. 

Now  I  may  say  without  contradiction:  that  all  the 
actions  of  rational  beings,  so  far  as  they  are  appear 
ances  (occurring  in  any  experience),  are  subject  to 
the  necessity  of  nature ;  but  the  same  actions,  as  re- 


H4  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

gards  merely  the  rational  subject  and  its  faculty  of 
acting  according  to  mere  reason,  are  free.  For  what 
is  required  for  the  necessity  of  nature?  Nothing  more 
than  the  determinability  of  every  event  in  the  world 
of  sense  according  to  constant  laws,  that  is,  a  refer 
ence  to  cause  in  the  appearance ;  in  this  process  the 
thing  in  itself  at  its  foundation  and  its  causality  re 
main  unknown.  But  I  say,  that  the  law  of  nature 
remains,  whether  the  rational  being  is  the  cause  of 
the  effects  in  the  sensuous  world  from  reason,  that  is, 
through  freedom,  or  whether  it  does  not  determine 
them  on  grounds  of  reason.  For,  if  the  former  is  the 
case,  the  action  is  performed  according  to  maxims, 
the  effect  of  which  as  appearance  is  always  conform 
able  to  constant  laws ;  if  the  latter  is  the  case,  and 
the  action  not  performed  on  principles  of  reason,  it 
is  subjected  to  the  empirical  laws  of  the  sensibility, 
and  in  both  cases  the  effects  are  connected  according 
to  constant  laws  ;  more  than  this  we  do  not  require 
or  know  concerning  natural  necessity.  But  in  the 
former  case  reason  is  the  cause  of  these  laws  of  na 
ture,  and  therefore  free ;  in  the  latter  the  effects  fol 
low  according  to  mere  natural  laws  of  sensibility,  be 
cause  reason  does  not  influence  it ;  but  reason  itself 
is  not  determined  on  that  account  by  the  sensibility, 
arid  is  therefore  free  in  this  case  too.  Freedom  is 
therefore  no  hindrance  to  natural  law  in  appearance, 
neither  does  this  law  abrogate  the  freedom  of  the 
practical  use  of  reason,  which  is  connected  with 
things  in  themselves,  as  determining  grounds. 

Thus  practical  freedom,  viz.,  the  freedom  in  which 
reason  possesses  causality  according  to  objectively 
determining  grounds,  is  rescued  and  yet  natural  ne 
cessity  is  not  in  the  least  curtailed  with  regard  to  the 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         115 

very  same  effects,  as  appearances.  The  same  remarks 
will  serve  to  explain  what  we  had  to  say  concerning 
transcendental  freedom  and  its  compatibility  with 
natural  necessity  (in  the  same  subject,  but  not  taken 
in  the  same  reference).  For,  as  to  this,  every  begin 
ning  of  the  action  of  a  being  from  objective  causes 
regarded  as  determining  grounds,  is  always  a  first 
start,  though  the  same  action  is  in  the  series  of  ap 
pearances  only  a  subordinate  start,  which  must  be 
preceded  by  a  state  of  the  cause,  which  determines  it, 
and  is  itself  determined  in  the  same  manner  by  an 
other  immediately  preceding.  Thus  we  are  able,  in 
rational  beings,  or  in  beings  generally,  so  far  as  their 
causality  is  determined  in  them  as  things  in  them 
selves,  to  imagine  a  faculty  of  beginning  from  itself 
a  series  of  states,  without  falling  into  contradiction 
with  the  laws  of  nature.  For  the  relation  of  the  ac 
tion  to  objective  grounds  of  reason  is  not  a  time-rela 
tion  ;  in  this  case  that  which  determines  the  causality 
does  not  precede  in  time  the  action,  because  such  de 
termining  grounds  represent  not  a  reference  to  objects 
of  sense,  e.  g.,  to  causes  in  the  appearances,  but  to 
determining  causes,  as  things  in  themselves,  which  do 
not  rank  under  conditions  of  time.  And  in  this  way 
the  action,  with  regard  to  the  causality  of  reason,  can 
be  considered  as  a  first  start  in  respect  to  the  series  of 
appearances,  and  yet  also  as  a  merely  subordinate  be 
ginning.  We  may  therefore  without  contradiction 
consider  it  in  the  former  aspect  as  free,  but  in  the 
latter  (in  so  far  as  it  is  merely  appearance)  as  subject 
to  natural  necessity. 

As  to  the  fourth  Antinomy,  it  is  solved  in  the  same 
way  as  the  conflict  of  reason  with  itself  in  the  third. 
For,  provided  the  cause  in  the  appearance  is  distin- 


u6  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

guished  from  the  cause  vfthe  appearance  (so  far  as  it 
can  be  thought  as  a  thing  in  itself),  both  propositions 
are  perfectly  reconcilable :  the  one,  that  there  is  no 
where  in  the  sensuous  world  a  cause  (according  to 
similar  laws  of  causality),  whose  existence  is  abso 
lutely  necessary;  the  other,  that  this  world  is  never 
theless  connected  with  a  Necessary  Being  as  its  cause 
(but  of  another  kind  and  according  to  another  law). 
The  incompatibility  of  these  propositions  entirely  rests 
upon  the  mistake  of  extending  what  is  valid  merely 
of  appearances  to  things  in  themselves,  and  in  gen 
eral  confusing  both  in  one  concept. 

§  54.  This  then  is  the  proposition  and  this  the  so 
lution  of  the  whole  antinomy,  in  which  reason  finds 
itself  involved  in  the  application  of  its  principles  to 
the  sensible  world.  The  former  alone  (the  mere  prop 
osition)  would  be  a  considerable  service  in  the  cause 
of  our  knowledge  of  human  reason,  even  though  the 
solution  might  fail  to  fully  satisfy  the  reader,  who  has 
here  to  combat  a  natural  illusion,  which  has  been  but 
recently  exposed  to  him,  and  which  he  had  hitherto 
always  regarded  as  genuine.  For  one  result  at  least 
is  unavoidable.  As  it  is  quite  impossible  to  prevent 
this  conflict  of  reason  with  itself — so  long  as  the  ob 
jects  of  the  sensible  world  are  taken  for  things  in 
themselves,  and  not  for  mere  appearances,  which  they 
are  in  fact — the  reader  is  thereby  compelled  to  ex 
amine  over  again  the  deduction  of  all  our  a  priori  cog 
nition  and  the  proof  which  I  have  given  of  my  deduc 
tion  in  order  to  come  to  a  decision  on  the  question. 
This  is  all  I  require  at  present ;  for  when  in  this  oc 
cupation  he  shall  have  thought  himself  deep  enough 
into  the  nature  of  pure  reason,  those  concepts  by 
which  alone  the  solution  of  the  conflict  of  reason  is 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE? 


possible,  will  become  sufficiently  familiar  to  him. 
Without  this  preparation  I  cannot  expect  an  unre 
served  assent  even  from  the  most  attentive  reader. 

III.    The  Theological  Idea  .  l 

§  55.  The  third  transcendental  Idea,  which  affords 
matter  for  the  most  important,  but,  if  pursued  only 
speculatively,  transcendent  and  thereby  dialectical 
use  of  reason,  is  the  ideal  of  pure  reason.  Reason  in 
this  case  does  not,  as  with  the  psychological  and  the 
cosmological  Ideas,  begin  from  experience,  and  err 
by  exaggerating  its  grounds,  in  striving  to  attain,  if 
possible,  the  absolute  completeness  of  their  series.  It 
rather  totally  breaks  with  experience,  and  from  mere 
concepts  of  what  constitutes  the  absolute  complete 
ness  of  a  thing  in  general,  consequently  by  means  of 
the  idea  of  a  most  perfect  primal  Being,  it  proceeds 
to  determine  the  possibility  and  therefore  the  actuality 
of  all  other  things.  And  so  the  mere  presupposition 
of  a  Being,  who  is  conceived  not  in  the  series  of  expe 
rience,  yet  for  the  purposes  of  experience  —  for  the 
sake  of  comprehending  its  connexion,  order,  and  unity 
—  i.  e.,  the  idea  [the  notion  of  it],  is  more  easily  distin 
guished  from  the  concept  of  the  understanding  here, 
than  in  the  former  cases.  Hence  we  can  easily  expose 
the  dialectical  illusion  which  arises  from  our  making 
the  subjective  conditions  of  our  thinking  objective 
conditions  of  objects  themselves,  and  an  hypothesis 
necessary  for  the  satisfaction  of  our  reason,  a  dogma. 
As  the  observations  of  the  Critiqtie  on  the  preten 
sions  of  transcendental  theology  are  intelligible,  clear, 
and  decisive,  I  have  nothing  more  to  add  on  the  sub 
ject. 

ICf.  Critique,  the  chapter  on  "Transcendental  Ideals." 


Ii8  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


General  Remark  on  the  Transcendental  Ideas. 

§  56.  The  objects,  which  are  given  us  by  experi 
ence,  are  in  many  respects  incomprehensible,  and 
many  questions,  to  which  the  law  of  nature  leads  us, 
when  carried  beyond  a  certain  point  (though  quite 
conformably  to  the  laws  of  nature),  admit  of  no  an 
swer;  as  for  example  the  question:  why  substances 
attract  one  another?  But  if  we  entirely  quit  nature, 
or  in  pursuing  its  combinations,  exceed  all  possible 
experience,  and  so  enter  the  realm  of  mere  ideas,  we 
cannot  then  say  that  the  object  is  incomprehensible, 
and  that  the  nature  of  things  proposes  to  us  insoluble 
problems.  For  we  are  not  then  concerned  with  na 
ture  or  in  general  with  given  objects,  but  with  con 
cepts,  which  have  their  origin  merely  in  our  reason, 
and  with  mere  creations  of  thought;  and  all  the  prob 
lems  that  arise  from  our  notions  of  them  must  be 
solved,  because  of  course  reason  can  and  must  give 
a  full  account  of  its  own  procedure.1  As  the  psycho 
logical,  cosmological,  and  theological  Ideas  are  noth 
ing  but  pure  concepts  of  reason,  which  cannot  be 
given  in  any  experience,  the  questions  which  reason 
asks  us  about  them  are  put  to  us  not  by  the  objects, 
but  by  mere  maxims  of  our  reason  for  the  sake  of  its 

1  Herr  Platner  in  his  Aphorisms  acutely  says  (§§  728,  729),  "  If  reason  be  a 
criterion,  no  concept,  which  is  incomprehensible  to  human  reason,  can  be 
possible.  Incomprehensibility  has  place  in  what  is  actual  only.  Here  in 
comprehensibility  arises  from  the  insufficiency  of  the  acquired  ideas."  It 
sounds  paradoxical,  but  is  otherwise  not  strange  to  say,  that  in  nature  there 
is  much  incomprehensible  (e.  g.,  the  faculty  of  generation)  but  if  we  mount 
still  higher,  and  even  go  beyond  nature,  everything  again  becomes  compre 
hensible;  for  we  then  quit  entirely  the  objects,  which  can  be  given  us,  and 
occupy  ourselves  merely  about  ideas,  in  which  occupation  we  can  easily 
comprehend  the  law  that  reason  prescribes  by  them  to  the  understanding  for 
its  use  in  experience,  because  the  law  is  the  reason's  own  production. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?        113 

own  satisfaction.  They  must  all  be  capable  of  satis 
factory  answers,  which  is  done  by  showing  that  they 
are  principles  which  bring  our  use  of  the  under 
standing  into  thorough  agreement,  completeness,  arid 
synthetical  unity,  and  that  they  so  far  hold  good  of 
experience  only,  but  of  experience  as  a  whole. 

Although  an  absolute  whole  of  experience  is  im 
possible,  the  idea  of  a  whole  of  cognition  according 
to  principles  must  impart  to  our  knowledge  a  peculiar 
kind  of  unity,  that  of  a  system,  without  which  it  is 
nothing  but  piecework,  and  cannot  be  used  for  prov 
ing  the  existence  of  a  highest  purpose  (which  can 
only  be  the  general  system  of  all  purposes),  I  do  not 
here  refer  only  to  the  practical,  but  also  to  the  high 
est  purpose  of  the  speculative  use  of  reason. 

The  transcendental  Ideas  therefore  express  the 
peculiar  application  of  reason  as  a  principle  of  syste 
matic  unity  in  the  use  of  the  understanding.  Yet  if 
we  assume  this  unity  of  the  mode  of  cognition  to  be 
attached  to  the  object  of  cognition,  if  we  regard  that 
which  is  merely  regulative  to  be  constitutive,  and  if 
we  persuade  ourselves  that  we  can  by  means  of  these 
Ideas  enlarge  our  cognition  transcendently,  or  far  be 
yond  all  possible  experience,  while  it  only  serves  to 
render  experience  within  itself  as  nearly  complete  as 
possible,  i.  e.,  to  limit  its  progress  by  nothing  that 
cannot  belong  to  experience  :  we  suffer  from  a  mere 
misunderstanding  in  our  estimate  of  the  proper  appli 
cation  of  our  reason  and  of  its  principles,  and  from  a 
Dialectic,  which  both  confuses  the  empirical  use  of 
reason,  and  also  sets  reason  at  variance  with  itself. 


120  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


CONCLUSION. 

On  the  Determination  of  the  Bounds  of  Pure  Reason. 

§  57.  Having  adduced  the  clearest  arguments,  it 
would  be  absurd  for  us  to  hope  that  we  can  know 
more  of  any  object,  than  belongs  to  the  possible  ex 
perience  of  it,  or  lay  claim  to  the  least  atom  of  knowl 
edge  about  anything  not  assumed  to  be  an  object  of 
possible  experience,  which  would  determine  it  accord 
ing  to  the  constitution  it  has  in  itself.  For  how  could 
we  determine  anything  in  this  way,  since  time,  space, 
and  the  categories,  and  still  more  all  the  concepts 
formed  by  empirical  experience  or  perception  in  the 
sensible  world  (Anschauung),  have  and  can  have  no 
other  use,  than  to  make  experience  possible.  And  if 
this  condition  is  omitted  from  the  pure  concepts  of 
the  understanding,  they  do  not  determine  any  object, 
and  have  no  meaning  whatever. 

But  it  would  be  on  the  other  hand  a  still  greater 
absurdity  if  we  conceded  no  things  in  themselves,  or 
set  up  our  experience  for  the  only  possible  mode  of 
knowing  things,  our  way  of  beholding  (Anschauung) 
them  in  space  and  in  time  for  the  only  possible  way, 
and  our  discursive  understanding  for  the  archetype  of 
every  possible  understanding ;  in  fact  if  we  wished  to 
have  the  principles  of  the  possibility  of  experience 
considered  universal  conditions  of  things  in  them 
selves. 

Our  principles,  which  limit  the  use  of  reason  to 
possible  experience,  might  in  this  way  become  tran 
scendent,  and  the  limits  of  our  reason  be  set  up  as 
limits  of  the  possibility  of  things  in  themselves  (as 


HOW  IS   METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         151 

Hume's  dialogues  mny  illustrate),  if  a  careful  critique 
did  not  guard  the  bounds  of  our  reason  with  respect 
to  its  empirical  use,  and  set  a  limit  to  its  pretensions. 
Scepticism  originally  arose  from  metaphysics  and  its 
licentious  dialectics.  At  first  it  might,  merely  to  favor 
the  empirical  use  of  reason,  announce  everything  that 
transcends  this  use  as  worthless  and  deceitful ;  but  by 
and  by,  when  it  was  perceived  that  the  very  same 
principles  that  are  used  in  experience,  insensibly,  and 
apparently  with  the  same  right,  led  still  further  than 
experience  extends,  then  men  began  to  doubt  even 
the  propositions  of  experience.  But  here  there  is  no 
danger;  for  common  sense  will  doubtless  always  as 
sert  its  rights.  A  certain  confusion,  however,  arose 
in  science  which  cannot  determine  how  far  reason  is 
to  be  trusted,  and  why  only  so  far  and  no  further,  and 
this  confusion  can  only  be  cleared  up  and  all  future 
relapses  obviated  by  a  formal  determination,  on  prin 
ciple,  of  the  boundary  of  the  use  of  our  reason. 

We  cannot  indeed,  beyond  all  possible  experience, 
form  a  definite  notion  of  what  things  in  themselves 
may  be.  Yet  we  are  not  at  liberty  to  abstain  entirely 
from  inquiring  into  them  ;  for  experience  never  satis 
fies  reason  fully,  but  in  answering  questions,  refers  us 
further  and  further  back,  and  leaves  us  dissatisfied 
with  regard  to  their  complete  solution.  This  any  one 
may  gather  from  the  Dialectics  of  pure  reason,  which 
therefore  has  its  good  subjective  grounds.  Having 
acquired,  as  regards  the  nature  of  our  soul,  a  clear 
conception  of  the  subject,  and  having  come  to  the 
conviction,  that  its  manifestations  cannot  be  explained 
materialistically,  who  can  refrain  from  asking  what 
the  soul  really  is,  and,  if  no  concept  of  experience 
suffices  for  the  purpose,  from  accounting  for  it  by  a 


122  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

concept  of  reason  (that  of  a  simple  immaterial  being), 
though  we  cannot  by  any  means  prove  its  objective 
reality?  Who  can  satisfy  himself  with  mere  empirical 
knowledge  in  all  the  cosmological  questions  of  the 
duration  and  of  the  quantity  of  the  world,  of  freedom 
or  of  natural  necessity,  since  every  answer  given  on 
principles  of  experience  begets  a  fresh  question,  which 
likewise  requires  its  answer  and  thereby  clearly  shows 
the  insufficiency  of  all  physical  modes  of  explanation 
to  satisfy  reason?  Finally,  who  does  not  see  in  the 
thorough-going  contingency  and  dependence  of  all  his 
thoughts  and  assumptions  on  mere  principles  of  ex 
perience,  the  impossibility  of  stopping  there?  And 
who  does  not  feel  himself  compelled,  notwithstanding 
all  interdictions  against  losing  himself  in  transcendent 
ideas,  to  seek  rest  and  contentment  beyond  all  the 
concepts  which  he  can  vindicate  by  experience,  in  the 
concept  of  a  Being,  the  possibility  of  which  we  can 
not  conceive,  but  at  the  same  time  cannot  be  refuted, 
because  it  relates  to  a  mere  being  of  the  understand 
ing,  and  without  it  reason  must  needs  remain  forever 
dissatisfied? 

Bounds  (in  extended  beings)  always  presuppose  a 
space  existing  outside  a  certain  definite  place,  and  in 
closing  it ;  limits  do  not  require  this,  but  are  mere 
negations,  which  affect  a  quantity,  so  far  as  it  is 
not  absolutely  complete.  But  our  reason,  as  it  were, 
sees  in  its  surroundings  a  space  for  the  cognition  of 
things  in  themselves,  though  we  can  never  have  defi 
nite  notions  of  them,  and  are  limited  to  appearances 
only. 

As  long  as  the  cognition  of  reason  is  homogene 
ous,  definite  bounds  to  it  are  inconceivable.  In  math 
ematics  and  in  natural  phflosophy  human  reason  ad- 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         123 

mits  of  limits,  but  not  of  bounds,  viz.,  that  something 
indeed  lies  without  it,  at  which  it  can  never  arrive, 
but  not  that  it  will  at  any  point  find  completion  in  its 
internal  progress.  The  enlarging  of  our  views  in  math 
ematics,  and  the  possibility  of  new  discoveries,  are 
infinite ;  and  the  same  is  the  case  with  the  discovery 
of  new  properties  of  nature,  of  new  powers  and  laws, 
by  continued  experience  and  its  rational  combination. 
But  limits  cannot  be  mistaken  here,  for  mathematics 
refers  to  appearances  only,  and  what  cannot  be  an  ob 
ject  of  sensuous  contemplation,  such  as  the  concepts 
of  metaphysics  and  of  morals,  lies  entirely  without  its 
sphere,  and  it  can  never  lead  to  them  ;  neither  does 
it  require  them.  It  is  therefore  not  a  continual  pro 
gress  and  an  approximation  towards  these  sciences, 
and  there  is  not,  as  it  were,  any  point  or  line  of  con 
tact.  Natural  science  will  never  reveal  to  us  the  in 
ternal  constitution  of  things,  which  though  not  ap 
pearance,  yet  can  serve  as  the  ultimate  ground  of 
explaining  appearance.  Nor  does  that  science  require 
this  for  its  physical  explanations.  Nay  even  if  such 
grounds  should  be  offered  from  other  sources  (for  in 
stance,  the  influence  of  immaterial  beings),  they  must 
be  rejected  and  not  used  in  the  progress  of  its  explana 
tions.  For  these  explanations  must  only  be  grounded 
upon  that  which  as  an  object  of  sense  can  belong  to 
experience,  and  be  brought  into  connexion  with  our 
actual  perceptions  and  empirical  laws. 

But  metaphysics  leads  us  towards  bounds  in  the 
dialectical  attempts  of  pure  reason  (not  undertaken 
arbitrarily  or  wantonly,  but  stimulated  thereto  by  the 
nature  of  reason  itself).  And  the  transcendental  Ideas, 
as  they  do  not  admit  of  evasion,  and  are  never  cap 
able  of  realisation,  serve  to  point  out  to  us  actually 


124  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

not  only  the  bounds  of  the  pure  use  of  reason,  but  also 
the  way  to  determine  them.  Such  is  the  end  and  the 
use  of  this  natural  predisposition  of  our  reason,  which 
has  brought  forth  metaphysics  as  its  favorite  child, 
whose  generation,  like  every  other  in  the  world,  is  not 
to  be  ascribed  to  blind  chance,  but  to  an  original 
germ,  wisely  organised  for  great  ends.  For  meta 
physics,  in  its  fundamental  features,  perhaps  more 
than  any  other  science,  is  placed  in  us  by  nature  it 
self,  and  cannot  be  considered  the  production  of  an 
arbitrary  choice  or  ,a  casual  enlargement  in  the  pro 
gress  of  experience  from  which  it  is  quite  disparate. 
Reason  with  all  its  concepts  and  laws  of  the  un 
derstanding,  which  suffice  for  empirical  use,  i.  e., 
within  the  sensible  world,  finds  in  itself  no  satisfaction 
because  ever-recurring  questions  deprive  us  of  all  hope 
of  their  complete  solution.  The  transcendental  ideas, 
which  have  that  completion  in  view,  are  such  prob 
lems  of  reason.  But  it  sees  clearly,  that  the  sensuous 
world  cannot  contain  this  completion,  neither  conse 
quently  can  all  the  concepts,  which  serve  merely  for 
understanding  the  world  of  sense,  such  as  space  and 
time,  and  whatever  we  have  adduced  under  the  name 
of  pure  concepts  of  the  understanding.  The  sensuous 
world  is  nothing  but  a  chain  of  appearances  connected 
according  to  universal  laws ;  it  has  therefore  no  sub 
sistence  by  itself;  it  is  not  the  thing  in  itself,  and 
consequently  must  point  to  that  which  contains  the 
basis  of  this  experience,  to  beings  which  cannot  be 
cognised  merely  as  phenomena,  but  as  things  in  them 
selves.  In  the  cognition  of  them  alone  reason  can 
hope  to  satisfy  its  desire  of  completeness  in  proceed 
ing  from  the  conditioned  to  its  conditions. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         125 

We  have  above  (§§  33,  34)  indicated  the  limits  of 
reason  with  regard  to  all  cognition  of  mere  creations 
of  thought.  Now,  since  the  transcendental  ideas  have 
urged  us  to  approach  them,  and  thus  have  led  us,  as 
it  were,  to  the  spot  where  the  occupied  space  (viz., 
experience)  touches  the  void  (that  of  which  we  can 
know  nothing,  viz.,  noumena),  we  can  determine  the 
bounds  of  pure  reason.  For  in  all  bounds  there  is 
something  positive  (e.  g.,  a  surface  is  the  boundary 
of  corporeal  space,  and  is  therefore  itself  a  space,  a 
line  is  a  space,  which  is  the  boundary  of  the  surface, 
a  point  the  boundary  of  the  line,  but  yet  always  a 
place  in  space),  whereas  limits  contain  mere  nega 
tions.  The  limits  pointed  out  in  those  paragraphs  are 
not  enough  after  we  have  discovered  that  beyond  them 
there  still  lies  something  (though  we  can  never  cog 
nise  what  it  is  in  itself).  For  the  question  now  is, 
What  is  the  attitude  of  our  reason  in  this  connexion 
of  what  we  know  with  what  we  do  not,  and  never  shall, 
know?  This  is  an  actual  connexion  of  a  known  thing 
with  one  quite  unknown  (and  which  will  always  re 
main  so),  and  though  what  is  unknown  should  not 
become  the  least  more  known — which  we  cannot  even 
hope — yet  the  notion  of  this  connexion  must  be  defi 
nite,  and  capable  of  being  rendered  distinct. 

We  must  therefore  accept  an  immaterial  being,  a 
world  of  understanding,  and  a  Supreme  Being  (all 
mere  noumena),  because  in  them  only,  as  things  in 
themselves,  reason  finds  that  completion  and  satisfac 
tion,  which  it  can  never  hope  for  in  the  derivation  of 
appearances  from  their  homogeneous  grounds,  and 
because  these  actually  have  reference  to  something 
distinct  from  them  (and  totally  heterogeneous),  as 
appearances  always  presuppose  an  object  in  itself, 


126  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

and  therefore  suggest  its  existence  whether  we  can 
know  more  of  it  or  not. 

But  as  we  can  never  cognise  these  beings  of  un 
derstanding  as  they  are  in  themselves,  that  is,  defi 
nitely,  yet  must  assume  them  as  regards  the  sensible 
world,  and  connect  them  with  it  by  reason,  we  are  at 
least  able  to  think  this  connexion  by  means  of  such 
concepts  as  express  their  relation  to  the  world  of 
sense.  Yet  if  we  represent  to  ourselves  a  being  of  the 
understanding  by  nothing  but  pure  concepts  of  the 
understanding,  we  then  indeed  represent  nothing  def 
inite  to  ourselves,  consequently  our  concept  has  no 
significance  ;  but  if  we  think  it  by  properties  borrowed 
from  the  sensuous  world,  it  is  no  longer  a  being  of  un 
derstanding,  but  is  conceived  as  an  appearance,  and 
belongs  to  the  sensible  world.  Let  us  take  an  in 
stance  from  the  notion  of  the  Supreme  Being. 

Our  deistic  conception  is  quite  a  pure  concept  of 
reason,  but  represents  only  a  thing  containing  all 
realities,  without  being  able  to  determine  any  one  of 
them;  because  for  that  purpose  an  example  must  be 
taken  from  the  world  of  sense,  in  which  case  we  should 
have  an  object  of  sense  only,  not  something  quite 
heterogeneous,  which  can  never  be  an  object  of  sense. 
Suppose  I  attribute  to  the  Supreme  Being  understand 
ing,  for  instance  ;  I  have  no  concept  of  an  understand 
ing  other  than  my  own,  one  that  must  receive  its  per 
ceptions  {Anschauung)  by  the  senses,  and  which  is 
occupied  in  bringing  them  under  rules  of  the  unity  of 
consciousness.  Then  the  elements  of  my  concept 
would  always  lie  in  the  appearance  ;  I  should  how 
ever  by  the  insufficiency  of  the  appearance  be  neces 
sitated  to  go  beyond  them  to  the  concept  of  a  being 
which  neither  depends  upon  appearance,  nor  is  bound 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         127 

up  with  them  as  conditions  of  its  determination.  But 
if  I  separate  understanding  from  sensibility  to  obtain 
a  pure  understanding,  then  nothing  remains  but  the 
mere  form  of  thinking  without  perception  (Anschau- 
ung},  by  which  form  alone  I  can  cognise  nothing  def 
inite,  and  consequently  no  object.  For  that  purpose 
I  should  conceive  another  understanding,  such  as 
would  directly  perceive  its  objects,1  but  of  which  I 
have  not  the  least  notion  ;  because  the  human  under 
standing  is  discursive,  and  can  [not  directly  perceive, 
it  can]  only  cognise  by  means  of  general  concepts. 
And  the  very  same  difficulties  arise  if  we  attribute  a 
will  to  the  Supreme  Being  ;  for  we  have  this  concept 
only  by  drawing  it  from  our  internal  experience,  and 
therefore  from  our  dependence  for  satisfaction  upon 
objects  whose  existence  we  require  ;  and  so  the  notion 
rests  upon  sensibility,  which  is  absolutely  incompatible 
with  the  pure  concept  of  the  Supreme  Being. 

Hume's  objections  to  deism  are  weak,  and  affect 
only  the  proofs,  and  not  the  deistic  assertion  itself. 
But  as  regards  theism,  which  depends  on  a  stricter 
determination  of  the  concept  of  the  Supreme  Being 
which  in  deism  is  merely  transcendent,  they  are  very 
strong,  and  as  this  concept  is  formed,  in  certain  (in 
fact  in  all  common)  cases  irrefutable.  Hume  always 
insists,  that  by  the  mere  concept  of  an  original  being, 
to  which  we  apply  only  ontological  predicates  (eter 
nity,  omnipresence,  omnipotence),  we  think  nothing 
definite,  and  that  properties  which  can  yield  a  con 
cept  in  concreto  must  be  superadded  ;  that  it  is  not 
enough  to  say,  it  is  Cause,  but  we  must  explain  the 
nature  of  its  causality,  for  example,  that  of  an  under 
standing  and  of  a  will.  He  then  begins  his  attacks 

IDer  die  Gegenstande  anschaute. 


128  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

on  the  essential  point  itself,  i.  e.,  theism,  as  he  had 
previously  directed  his  battery  only  against  the  proofs 
of  deism,  an  attack  which  is  not  very  dangerous  to  it 
in  its  consequences.  All  his  dangerous  arguments 
refer  to  anthropomorphism,  which  he  holds  to  be  in 
separable  from  theism,  and  to  make  it  absurd  in  it 
self;  but  if  the  former  be  abandoned,  the  latter  must 
vanish  with  it,  and  nothing  remain  but  deism,  of  which 
nothing  can  come,  which  is  of  no  value,  and  which 
cannot  serve  as  any  foundation  to  religion  or  morals. 
If  this  anthropomorphism  were  really  unavoidable,  no 
proofs  whatever  of  the  existence  of  a  Supreme  Being, 
even  were  they  all  granted,  could  determine  for  us  the 
concept  of  this  Being  without  involving  us  in  contra 
dictions. 

If  we  connect  with  the  command  to  avoid  all  tran 
scendent  judgments  of  pure  reason,  the  command 
(which  apparently  conflicts  with  it)  to  proceed  to  con 
cepts  that  lie  beyond  the  field  of  its  immanent  (em 
pirical)  use,  we  discover  that  both  can  subsist  to 
gether,  but  only  at  the  boundary  of  all  lawful  use  of 
reason.  For  this  boundary  belongs  as  well  to  the  field 
of  experience,  as  to  that  of  the  creations  of  thought, 
and  we  are  thereby  taught,  as  well,  how  these  so  re 
markable  ideas  serve  merely  for  marking  the  bounds 
of  human  reason.  On  the  one  hand  they  give  warning 
not  boundlessly  to  extend  cognition  of  experience,  as 
if  nothing  but  world1  remained  for  us  to  cognise,  and 
yet,  on  the  other  hand,  not  to  transgress  the  bounds 
of  experience,  and  to  think  of  judging  about  things 
beyond  them,  as  things  in  themselves. 

But  we  stop  at  this  boundary  if  we  limit  our  judg- 

IThe  use  of  the  word  "  world  "  without  article,  though  odd,  seems  to  be 
the  correct  reading,  but  it  may  be  a  mere  misprint. — Ed. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?        I2Q 

ment  merely  to  the  relation  which  the  world  may  have 
to  a  Being  whose  very  concept  lies  beyond  all  the 
knowledge  which  we  can  attain  within  the  world.  For 
we  then  do  not  attribute  to  the  Supreme  Being  any  of 
the  properties  in  themselves,  by  which  we  represent 
objects  of  experience,  and  thereby  avoid  dogmatic  an 
thropomorphism ;  but  we  attribute  them  to  his  rela 
tion  to  the  world,  and  allow  ourselves  a  symbolical 
anthropomorphism,  which  in  fact  concerns  language 
only,  and  not  the  object  itself. 

If  I  say  that  we  are  compelled  to  consider  the 
world,  as  if  it  were  the  work  of  a  Supreme  Under 
standing  and  Will,  I  really  say  nothing  more,  than 
that  a  watch,  a  ship,  a  regiment,  bears  the  same  rela 
tion  to  the  watchmaker,  the  shipbuilder,  the  com 
manding  officer,  as  the  world  of  sense  (or  whatever 
constitutes  the  substratum  of  this  complex  of  appear 
ances)  does  to  the  Unknown,  which  I  do  not  hereby 
cognise  as  it  is  in  itself,  but  as  it  is  for  me  or  in  rela 
tion  to  the  world,  of  which  I  am  a  part. 

§  58.  Such  a  cognition  is  one  of  analogy,  and  does 
not  signify  (as  is  commonly  understood)  an  imperfect 
similarity  of  two  things,  but  a  perfect  similarity  of  rela 
tions  between  two  quite  dissimilar  things.1  By  means 


1  There  is,  e  g.,  an  analogy  between  the  juridical  relation  of  human  actions 
and  the  mechanical  relation  of  motive  powers.  I  never  can  do  anything  to  an 
other  man  without  giving  him  a  right  to  do  the  same  to  me  on  the  same  con 
ditions  ;  just  as  no  mass  can  act  with  its  motive  power  on  another  mass  with 
out  thereby  occasioning  the  other  to  react  equally  against  it.  Here  right  and 
motive  power  are  quite  dissimilar  things,  but  in  their  relation  there  is  com 
plete  similarity.  By  means  of  such  an  analogy  I  can  obtain  a  notion  of  the 
relation  of  things  which  absolutely  are  unknown  to  me.  For  instance,  as  the 
promotion  of  the  welfare  of  children  (=  a)  is  to  the  love  of  parents  (=  b),  so 
the  welfare  of  the  human  species  (=  c)  is  to  that  unknown  [quantity  which  is] 
in  God  (=x),  which  we  call  love;  not  as  if  it  had  the  least  similarity  to  any 
human  inclination,  but  because  we  can  suppose  its  relation  to  the  world  to 
be  similar  to  that  which  things  of  the  world  bear  one  another.  But  the  con- 


130  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

of  this  analogy,  however,  there  remains  a  concept  of 
the  Supreme  Being  sufficiently  determined  for  us, 
though  we  have  left  out  everything  that  could  deter 
mine  it  absolutely  or  in  itself;  for  we  determine  it  as 
regards  the  world  and  as  regards  ourselves,  and  more 
do  we  not  require.  The  attacks  which  Hume  makes 
upon  those  who  would  determine  this  concept  abso 
lutely,  by  taking  the  materials  for  so  doing  from 
themselves  and  the  world,  do  not  affect  us ;  and  he 
cannot  object  to  us,  that  we  have  nothing  left  if  we 
give  up  the  objective  anthropomorphism  of  the  con 
cept  of  the  Supreme  Being. 

For  let  us  assume  at  the  outset  (as  Hume  in  his 
dialogues  makes  Philo  grant  Cleanthes),  as  a  neces 
sary  hypothesis,  the  deistical  concept  of  the  First  Be 
ing,  in  which  this  Being  is  thought  by  the  mere  onto- 
logical  predicates  of  substance,  of  cause,  etc.  This 
must  be  done,  because  reason,  actuated  in  the  sen 
sible  world  by  mere  conditions,  which  are  themselves 
always  conditional,  cannot  otherwise  have  any  satis 
faction,  and  it  therefore  can  be  done  without  falling 
into  anthropomorphism  (which  transfers  predicates 
from  the  world  of  sense  to  a  Being  quite  distinct  from 
the  world),  because  those  predicates  are  mere  catego 
ries,  which,  though  they  do  not  give  a  determinate 
concept  of  God,  yet  give  a  concept  not  limited  to  any 
conditions  of  sensibility.  Thus  nothing  can  prevent 
our  predicating  of  this  Being  a  causality  through  rea 
son  with  regard  to  the  world,  and  thus  passing  to  the 
ism,  without  being  obliged  to  attribute  to  God  in 
himself  this  kind  of  reason,  as  a  property  inhering  in 
him.  For  as  to  the  former,  the  only  possible  way  of 

cept  of  relation  in  this  case  is  a  mere  category,  viz.,  the  concept  of  cause, 
which  has  nothing  to  do  with  sensibility. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         13! 

prosecuting  the  use  of  reason  (as  regards  all  possible 
experience,  in  complete  harmouy  with  itself)  in  the 
world  of  sense  to  the  highest  point,  is  to  assume  a 
supreme  reason  r.s  a  cause  of  all  the  connexions  in 
the  world.  Such  a  principle  must  be  quite  advantage 
ous  to  reason  and  can  hurt  it  nowhere  in  its  applica 
tion  to  nature.  As  to  the  latter,  reason  is  thereby 
not  transferred  as  a  property  to  the  First  Being  in 
himself,  but  only  to  his  relation  to  the  world  of  sense, 
and  so  anthropomorphism  is  entirely  avoided.  For 
nothing  is  considered  here  but  the  cause  of  the  form 
of  reason  which  is  perceived  everywhere  in  the  world, 
and  reason  is  attributed  to  the  Supreme  Being,  so  far 
as  it  contains  the  ground  of  this  form  of  reason  in  the 
world,  but  according  to  analogy  only,  that  is,  so  far 
as  this  expression  shows  merely  the  relation,  which 
the  Supreme  Cause  unknown  to  us  has  to  the  world, 
in  order  to  determine  everything  in  it  conformably  to 
reason  in  the  highest  degree.  We  are  thereby  kept 
from  using  reason  as  an  attribute  for  the  purpose  of 
conceiving  God,  but  instead  of  conceiving  the  world 
in  such  a  manner  as  is  necessary  to  have  the  greatest 
possible  use  of  reason  according  to  principle.  We 
thereby  acknowledge  that  the  Supreme  Being  is  quite 
inscrutable  and  even  unthinkable  in  any  definite  way 
as  to  what  he  is  in  himself.  We  are  thereby  kept,  on 
the  one  hand,  from  making  a  transcendent  use  of  the 
concepts  which  we  have  of  reason  as  an  efficient  cause 
(by  means  of  the  will),  in  order  to  determine  the  Di 
vine  Nature  by  properties,  which  are  only  borrowed 
from  human  nature,  and  from  losing  ourselves  in 
gross  and  extravagant  notions,  and  on  the  other  hand 
from  deluging  the  contemplation  of  the  world  with 
hyperphysical  modes  of  explanation  according  to  our 


132  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

notions  of  human  reason,  which  we  transfer  to  God, 
and  so  losing  for  this  contemplation  its  proper  appli 
cation,  according  to  which  it  should  be  a  rational 
study  of  mere  nature,  and  not  a  presumptuous  deriva 
tion  of  its  appearances  from  a  Supreme  Reason.  The 
expression  suited  to  our  feeble  notions  is,  that  we  con 
ceive  the  world  as  if  it  came,  as  to  its  existence  and 
internal  plan,  from  a  Supreme  Reason,  by  which  no 
tion  we  both  cognise  the  constitution,  which  belongs 
to  the  world  itself,  yet  without  pretending  to  deter 
mine  the  nature  of  its  cause  in  itself,  and  on  the  other 
hand,  \\e  transfer  the  ground  of  this  constitution  (of 
the  form  of  reason  in  the  world)  upon  the  relation  of 
the  Supreme  Cause  to  the  world,  without  finding  the 
world  sufficient  by  itself  for  that  purpose.1 

Thus  the  difficulties  which  seem  to  oppose  theism 
disappear  by  combining  with  Hume's  principle — "not 
to  carry  the  use  of  reason  dogmatically  beyond  the 
field  of  all  possible  experience" — this  other  principle, 
which  he  quite  overlooked  :  "not  to  consider  the  field 
of  experience  as  one  which  bounds  itself  in  the  eye  of 
our  reason."  The  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  here  points 
out  the  true  mean  between  dogmatism,  which  Hume 
combats,  and  skepticism,  which  he  would  substitute 
for  it — a  mean  which  is  not  like  other  means  that  we 
find  advisable  to  determine  for  ourselves  as  it  were 
mechanically  (by  adopting  something  from  one  side 
and  something  from  the  other),  and  by  which  nobody 

1 1  may  say,  that  the  causality  of  the  Supreme  Cause  holds  the  same 
place  with  regard  to  the  world  that  human  reason  does  with  regard  to  its 
works  of  art.  Here  the  nature  of  the  Supreme  Cause  itself  remains  unknown 
to  me  :  I  only  compare  its  effects  (the  order  of  the  world)  which  I  know,  and 
their  conformity  to  reason,  to  the  effects  of  human  reason  which  I  also  know; 
and  hence  I  term  the  former  reason,  without  attributing  to  it  on  that  account 
what  I  understand  in  man  by  this  term,  or  attaching  to  it  anything  else 
known  to  me,  as  its  property. 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         133 

is  taught  a  better  way,  but  such  a  one  as  can  be  ac 
curately  determined  on  principles. 

§  59.  At  the  beginning  of  this  annotation  I  made 
use  of  the  metaphor  of  a  boundary,  in  order  to  estab-  v 
lish  the  limits  of  reason  in  regard  to  its  suitable  use. 
The  world  of  sense  contains  merely  appearances, 
which  are  not  things  in  themselves,  but  the  under 
standing  must  assume  these  latter  ones,  viz.,  noumena. 
In  our  reason  both  are  comprised,  and  the  question 
is,  How  does  reason  proceed  to  set  boundaries  to  the 
understanding  as  regards  both  these  fields?  Experi 
ence,  which  contains  all  that  belongs  to  the  sensuous 
world,  does  not  bound  itself;  it  only  proceeds  in 
every  case  from  the  conditioned  to  some  other  equally 
conditioned  object.  Its  boundary  must  lie  quite  with 
out  it,  and  this  field  is  that  of  the  pure  beings  of  the 
understanding.  But  this  field,  so  far  as  the  determi 
nation  of  the  nature  of  these  beings  is  concerned,  is 
an  empty  space  for  us,  and  if  dogmatically-determined 
concepts  alone  are  in  question,  we  cannot  pass  out  of 
the  field  of  possible  experience.  But  as  a  boundary 
itself  is  something  positive,  which  belongs  as  well  to 
that  which  lies  within,  as  to  the  space  that  lies  with 
out  the  given  complex,  it  is  still  an  actual  positive 
cognition,  which  reason  only  acquires  by  enlarging 
itself  to  this  boundary,  yet  without  attempting  to  pass 
it;  because  it  there  finds  itself  in  the  presence  of  an 
empty  space,  in  which  it  can  conceive  forms  of  things, 
but  not  things  themselves.  But  the  setting  of  a  bound 
ary  to  the  field  of  the  understanding  by  something, 
which  is  otherwise  unknown  to  it,  is  still  a  cognition 
which  belongs  to  reason  even  at  this  standpoint,  and 
by  which  it  is  neither  confined  within  the  sensible, 
nor  straying  without  it,  but  only  refers,  as  befits  the 


134  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

knowledge  of  a  boundary,  to  the  relation  between  that 
which  lies  without  it,  and  that  which  is  contained 
within  it. 

Natural  theology  is  such  a  concept  at  the  bound 
ary  of  human  reason,  being  constrained  to  look  be 
yond  this  boundary  to  the  Idea  of  a  Supreme  Being 
(and,  for  practical  purposes  to  that  of  an  intelligible 
world  also),  not  in  order  to  determine  anything  rela 
tively  to  this  pure  creation  of  the  understanding,  which 
lies  beyond  the  world  of  sense,  but  in  order  to  guide 
the  use  of  reason  within  it  according  to  principles  of 
the  greatest  possible  (theoretical  as  well  as  practical) 
unity.  For  this  purpose  we  make  use  of  the  reference 
of  the  world  of  sense  to  an  independent  reason,  as  the 
cause  of  all  its  connexions.  Thereby  we  do  not  purely 
invent  a  being,  but,  as  beyond  the  sensibl&  world 
there  must  be  something  that  can  only  be  thought  by 
the  pure  understanding,  we  determine  that  something 
in  this  particular  way,  though  only  of  course  accord 
ing  to  analogy. 

And  thus  there  remains  our  original  proposition, 
which  is  the  rtsumt  of  the  whole  Critique:  "that  rea 
son  by  all  its  a  priori  principles  never  teaches  us  any 
thing  more  than  objects  of  possible  experience,  and 
even  of  these  nothing  more  than  can  be  cognised  in 
experience."  But  this  limitation  does  not  prevent 
reason  leading  us  to  the  objective  boundary  of  experi 
ence,  viz.,  to  the  reference  to  something  which  is  not 
itself  an  object  of  experience,  but  is  the  ground  of  all 
experience.  Reason  does  not  however  teach  us  any 
thing  concerning  the  thing  in  itself:  it  only  instructs 
us  as  regards  its  own  complete  and  highest  use  in  the 
field  of  possible  experience.  But  this  is  all  that  can 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?        135 

be  reasonably  desired  in  the  present  case,  and  with 
which  we  have  cause  to  be  satisfied. 

§  60.  Thus  we  have  fully  exhibited  metaphysics  as 
it  is  actually  given  in  the  natural  predisposition  of  hu 
man  reason,  and  in  that  which  constitutes  the  essen 
tial  end  of  its  pursuit,  according  to  its  subjective  pos 
sibility.  Though  we  have  found,  that  this  merely 
natural  use  of  such  a  predisposition  of  our  reason,  if 
no  discipline  arising  only  from  a  scientific  critique 
bridles  and  sets  limits  to  it,  involves  us  in  transcendent, 
either  apparently  or  really  conflicting,  dialectical  syl 
logisms  ;  and  this  fallacious  metaphysics  is  not  only 
unnecessary  as  regards  the  promotion  of  our  knowl 
edge  of  nature,  but  even  disadvantageous  to  it :  there 
yet  remains  a  problem  worthy  of  solution,  which  is  to 
find  out  the  natural  ends  intended  by  this  disposition 
to  transcendent  concepts  in  our  reason,  because  every 
thing  that  lies  in  nature  must  be  originally  intended 
for  some  useful  purpose. 

Such  an  inquiry  is  of  a  doubtful  nature;  and  I 
acknowledge,  that  what  I  can  say  about  it  is  conjec 
ture  only,  like  every  speculation  about  the  first  ends 
of  nature.  The  question  does  not  concern  the  objec 
tive  validity  of  metaphysical  judgments,  but  our  nat 
ural  predisposition  to  them,  and  therefore  does  not 
belong  to  the  system  of  metaphysics  but  to  anthro 
pology. 

When  I  compare  all  the  transcendental  Ideas,  the 
totality  of  which  constitutes  the  particular  problem  of 
natural  pure  reason,  compelling  it  to  quit  the  mere 
contemplation  of  nature,  to  transcend  all  possible  ex 
perience,  and  in  this  endeavor  to  produce  the  thing 
(be  it  knowledge  or  fiction)  called  metaphysics,  I  think 
I  perceive  that  the  aim  of  this  natural  tendency  is,  to 


136  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

free  our  notions  from  the  fetters  of  experience  and 
from  the  limits  of  the  mere  contemplation  of  nature 
so  far  as  at  least  to  open  to  us  a  field  containing  mere 
objects  for  the  pure  understanding,  which  no  sensi 
bility  can  reach,  not  indeed  for  the  purpose  of  specu- 
latively  occupying  ourselves  with  them  (for  there  we 
can  find  no  ground  to  stand  on),  but  because  practical 
principles,  which,  without  finding  some  such  scope 
for  their  necessary  expectation  and  hope,  could  not 
expand  to  the  universality  which  reason  unavoidably 
requires  from  a  moral  point  of  view. 

So  I  find  that  the  Psychological  Idea  (however 
little  it  may  reveal  to  me  the  nature  of  the  human 
soul,  which  is  higher  than  all  concepts  of  experience), 
shows  the  insufficiency  of  these  concepts  plainly 
enough,  and  thereby  deters  me  from  materialism,  the 
psychological  notion  of  which  is  unfit  for  any  explana 
tion  of  nature,  and  besides  confines  reason  in  prac 
tical  respects.  The  Cosmological  Ideas,  by  the  ob 
vious  insufficiency  of  all  possible  cognition  of  nature 
to  satisfy  reason  in  its  lawful  inquiry,  serve  in  the 
same  manner  to  keep  us  from  naturalism,  which  as 
serts  nature  to  be  sufficient  for  itself.  Finally,  all 
natural  necessity  in  the  sensible  world  is  conditional, 
as  it  always  presupposes  the  dependence  of  things 
upon  others,  and  unconditional  necessity  must  be 
sought  only  in  the  unity  of  a  cause  different  from  the 
world  of  sense.  But  as  the  causality  of  this  cause,  in 
its  turn,  were  it  merely  nature,  could  never  render 
the  existence  of  the  contingent  (as  its  consequent) 
comprehensible,  reason  frees  itself  by  means  of  the 
Theological  Idea  from  fatalism,  (both  as  a  blind  nat 
ural  necessity  in  the  coherence  of  nature  itself,  with 
out  a  first  principle,  and  as  a  blind  causality  of  this 


HOW  IS   METAPHYSICS  IN  GENERAL  POSSIBLE?         137 

principle  itself),  and  leads  to  the  concept  of  a  cause 
possessing  freedom,  or  of  a  Supreme  Intelligence. 
Thus  the  transcendental  Ideas  serve,  if  not  to  instruct 
us  positively,  at  least  to  destroy  the  rash  assertions  of 
Materialism,  of  Naturalism,  and  of  Fatalism,  and  thus 
to  afford  scope  for  the  moral  Ideas  beyond  the  field  of 
speculation.  These  considerations,  I  should  think, 
explain  in  some  measure  the  natural  predisposition  of 
which  I  spoke. 

The  practical  value,  which  a  merely  speculative 
science  may  have,  lies  without  the  bounds  of  this  sci 
ence,  and  can  therefore  be  considered  as  a  scholion 
merely,  and  like  all  scholia  does  not  form  part  of  the 
science  itself.  This  application  however  surely  lies 
within  the  bounds  of  philosophy,  especially  of  philos 
ophy  drawn  from  the  pure  sources  of  reason,  where 
us  speculative  use  in  metaphysics  must  necessarily  be 
at  unity  with  its  practical  use  in  morals.  Hence  the 
unavoidable  dialectics  of  pure  reason,  considered  in 
metaphysics,  as  a  natural  tendency,  deserves  to  be 
explained  not  as  an  illusion  merely,  which  is  to  be  re 
moved,  but  also,  if  possible,  as  a  natural  provision  as 
regards  its  end,  though  this  duty,  a  work  of  super 
erogation,  cannot  justly  be  assigned  to  metaphysics 
proper. 

The  solutions  of  these  questions  which  are  treated 
in  the  chapter  on  the  Regulative  Use  of  the  Ideas  of 
Pure  Reason1  should  be  considered  a  second  scholion 
which  however  has  a  greater  affinity  with  the  subject 
of  metaphysics.  For  there  certain  rational  principles 
are  expounded  which  determine  a  priori  the  order  of 
nature  or  rather  of  the  understanding,  which  seeks 
nature's  laws  through  experience.  They  seem  to  be 

1  Critique  of  Pure  Reason,  II.,  chap.  III.,  section  7. 


138  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

constitutive  and  legislative  with  regard  to  experience, 
though  they  spring  from  pure  reason,  which  cannot 
be  considered,  like  the  understanding,  as  a  principle 
of  possible  experience.  Now  whether  or  not  this  har 
mony  rests  upon  the  fact,  that  just  as  nature  does  not 
inhere  in  appearances  or  in  their  source  (the  sensibil 
ity)  itself,  but  only  in  so  far  as  the  latter  is  in  relation 
to  the  understanding,  as  also  a  systematic  unity  in 
applying  the  understanding  to  bring  about  an  entirety 
of  all  possible  experience  can  only  belong  to  the  un 
derstanding  when  in  relation  to  reason  ;  and  whether 
or  not  experience  is  in  this  way  mediately  subordinate 
to  the  legislation  of  reason  :  may  be  discussed  by 
those  who  desire  to  trace  the  nature  of  reason  even 
beyond  its  use  in  metaphysics,  into  the  general  prin 
ciples  of  a  history  of  nature ;  I  have  represented  this 
task  as  important,  but  not  attempted  its  solution,  in 
the  book  itself.1 

And  thus  I  conclude  the  analytical  solution  of  the 
main  question  which  I  had  proposed :  How  is  meta 
physics  in  general  possible?  by  ascending  from  the 
data  of  its  actual  use  in  its  consequences,  to  the 
grounds  of  its  possibility. 

^Throughout  in  the  Critique  I  never  lost  sight  of  the  plan  not  to  neglect 
anything,  were  it  ever  so  recondite,  that  could  render  the  inquiry  into  the 
nature  of  pure  reason  complete.  Everybody  may  afterwards  carry  his  re 
searches  as  far  as  he  pleases,  when  he  has  been  merely  shown  what  yet  re 
mains  to  be  done.  It  is  this  a  duty  which  must  reasonably  be  expected  of 
him  who  has  made  it  his  business  to  survey  the  whole  field,  in  order  to  con 
sign  it  to  others  for  future  cultivation  and  allotment.  And  to  this  branch 
both  the  scholia  belong,  which  will  hardly  recommend  themselves  by  their 
dryness  to  amateurs,  and  hence  are  added  here  for  connoisseurs  only. 


SCHOLIA. 

SOLUTION    OF    THE    GENERAL    QUESTION    OF    THE 

PROLEGOMENA,   "HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS 

POSSIBLE  AS  A  SCIENCE?" 

METAPHYSICS,  as  a  natural  disposition  of  rea 
son,  is  actual,  but  if  considered  by  itself  alone 
(as  the  analytical  solution  of  the  third  principal  ques 
tion  showed),  dialectical  and  illusory.  If  we  think  of 
taking  principles  from  it,  and  in  using  them  follow 
the  natural,  but  on  that  account  not  less  false,  illu 
sion,  we  can  never  produce  science,  but  only  a  vain 
dialectical  art,  in  which  one  school  may  outdo  an 
other,  but  none  can  ever  acquire  a  just  and  lasting 
approbation. 

In  order  that  as  a  science  metaphysics  may  be  en 
titled  to  claim  not  mere  fallacious  plausibility,  but  in 
sight  and  conviction,  a  Critique  of  Reason  must  itself 
exhibit  the  whole  stock  of  a  priori  concepts,  their  di 
vision  according  to  their  various  sources  (Sensibilit)', 
Understanding,  and  Reason),  together  with  a  com 
plete  table  of  them,  the  analysis  of  all  these  concepts, 
with  all  their  consequences,  especially  by  means  of 
the  deduction  of  these  concepts,  the  possibility  of 
synthetical  cognition  a  priori,  the  principles  of  its  ap 
plication  and  finally  its  bounds,  all  in  a  complete  sys 
tem.  Critique,  therefore,  and  critique _  alone,  contains 
in  itself  the_ffihol&  well- proved  and  well- tested  plan, 


140  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

and  even  all  the  means  required  to  accomplish  meta 
physics,  as  a  science;  by  other  ways  and  means  it  is 
impossible.  The  question  here  tlxTefore  is  not  so 
much  how  this  performance  is  possible,  as  how  to  set 
it  going,  and  induce  men  of  clear  heads  to  quit  their 
hitherto  perverted  and  fruitless  cultivation  for  one 
that  will  not  deceive,  and  how  such  a  union  for  the 
common  end  may  best  be  directed. 

This  much  is  certain,  that  whoever  has  once  tasted 
Critique  will  be  ever  after  disgusted  with  all  dogmati 
cal  twaddle  which  he  formerly  put  up  with,  because 
his  reason  must  have  something,  and  could  find  noth 
ing  better  for  its  support. 

Critique  stands  in  the  same  relation  to  the  com 
mon  metaphysics  of  the  schools,  as  chemistry  does  to 
alchemy,  or  as  astronomy  to  the  astrology  of  the  for 
tune-teller.  I  pledge  myself  that  nobody  who  has 
read  through  and  through,  and  grasped  the  principles 
of,  the  Critique  even  in  these  Prolegomena  only,  will 
ever  return  to  that  old  and  sophistical  pseudo-science; 
but  will  rather  with  a  certain  delight  look  forward  to 
metaphysics  which  is  now  indeed  in  his  power,  re 
quiring  no  more  preparatory  discoveries,  and  now  at 
last  affording  permanent  satisfaction  to  reason.  For 
here  is  an  advantage  upon  which,  of  all  possible  sci 
ences,  metaphysics  alone  can  with  certainty  reckon  : 
that  it  can  be  brought  to  such  completion  and  fixity 
as  to  be  incapable  of  further  change,  or  of  any  aug 
mentation  by  new  discoveries;  because  here  reason 
has  Jhe_sources  of  its  knowledge  in  itself,  not  in  pb- 
jects^  and  their  observation  (Anschauung),  by  which 
latterjts  stock  of  knowledge  cannot  be  further  in 
creased.  When  then-fore  it  has  exhibited  the  funda 
mental  laws  of  its  faculty  completely  and  so  definitely 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  POSSIBLE  AS  A  SCIENCE?       14! 

as  to  avoid  all  misunderstanding,  there  remains  noth 
ing  for  pure  reason  to  cognise  a  priori,  nay,  there  is 
even  no  ground  to  raise  further  questions.  The  sure 
prospect  of  knowledge  so  definite  and  so  compact  has 
a  peculiar  charm,  even  though  we  should  set  aside  all 
its  advantages,  of  which  I  shall  hereafter  speak. 

All  false  art,  all  vain  wisdom,  lasts  its  time,  but 
finally  destroys  itself,  and  its  highest  culture  is  also 
the  epoch  of  its  decay.  That  this  time  is  come  for 
metaphysics  appears  from  the  state  into  which  it  has 
fallen  among  all  learned  nations,  despite  of  all  the 
zeal  with  which  other  sciences  of  every  kind  are  pros 
ecuted.  The  old  arrangement  of  our  university  studies 
still  preserves  its  shadow ;  now  and  then  an  Academy 
of  Science  tempts  men  by  offering  prizes  to  write 
essays  on  it,  but  it  is  no  longer  numbered  among 
thorough  sciences  ;  and  let  any  one  judge  for  himself 
how  a  man  of  genius,  if  he  were  called  a  great  meta 
physician,  would  receive  the  compliment,  which  may 
be  well-meant,  but  is  scarce  envied  by  anybody. 

Yet,  though  the  period  of  the  downfall  of  all  dog 
matical  metaphysics  has  undoubtedly  arrived,  we  are 
yet  far  from  being  able  to  say  that  the  period  of  its 
regeneration  is  come  by  means  of  a  thorough  and 
complete  Critique  of  Reason.  All  transitions  from  a 
tendency  to  its  contrary  pass  through  the  stage  of  in 
difference,  and  this  moment  is  the  most  dangerous  for 
an  author,  but,  in  my  opinion,  the  most  favorable  for 
the  science.  For,  when  party  spirit  has  died  out  by 
a  total  dissolution  of  former  connexions,  minds  are  in 
the  best  state  to  listen  to  several  proposals  for  an  or 
ganisation  according  to  a  new  plan. 

When  I  say,  that  I  hope  these  Prolegomena  will 
excite  investigation  in  the  field  of  critique  and  afford 


a  new  and  promising  object  to  sustain  the  general 
spirit  of  philosophy,  which  seems  on  its  speculative 
side  to  want  sustenance,  I  can  imagine  beforehand, 
that  every  one,  whom  the  thorny  paths  of  my  Critique 
have  tired  and  put  out  of  humor,  will  ask  me,  upon 
what  I  found  this  hope.  My  answer  is,  upon  the  irre 
sistible  law  of  necessity. 

That  the  human  mind  will  ever  give  up  metaphys 
ical  researches  is  as  little  to  be  expected  as  that  we 
should  prefer  to  give  up  breathing  altogether,  to  avoid 
inhaling  impure  air.  There  will  therefore  always  be 
metaphysics  in  the  world  ;  nay,  every  one,  especially 
every  man  of  reflexion,  will  have  it,  and  for  want  of  a 
recognised  standard,  will  shape  it  for  himself  after  his 
own  pattern.  What  has  hitherto  been  called  meta 
physics,  cannot  satisfy  any  critical  mind,  but  to  forego 
it  entirely  is  impossible  ;  therefore  a  Critique  of  Pure 
Reason  itself  must  now  be  attempted  or,  if  one  exists, 
investigated,  and  brought  to  the  full  test,  because 
there  is  no  other  means  of  supplying  this  pressing 
want,  which  is  something  more  than  mere  thirst  for 
knowledge. 

Ever  since  I  have  come  to  know  critique,  when 
ever  I  finish  reading  a  book  of  metaphysical  contents, 
which,  by  the  preciseness  of  its  notions,  by  variety, 
order,  and  an  easy  style,  was  not  only  entertaining 
but  also  helpful,  I  cannot  help  asking,  "  Has  this 
author  indeed  advanced  metaphysics  a  single  step?" 
The  learned  men,  whose  works  have  been  useful  to 
me  in  other  respects  and  always  contributed  to  the 
culture  of  my  mental  powers,  will,  I  hope,  forgive  me 
for  saying,  that  I  have  never  been  able  to  find  either 
their  essays  or  my  own  less  important  ones  (though 
self-love  may  recommend  them  to  me)  to  have  ad- 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  POSSIBLE  AS  A  SCIENCE?       143 

vanced  the  science  of  metaphysics  in  the  least,  and 
why? 

Here  is  the  very  obvious  reason  :  metaphysics  did 
not  then  exist  as  a  science,  nor  can  it  be  gathered 
piecemeal,  but  its  germ  must  be  fully  preformed  in 
the  Critique.  But  in  order  to  prevent  all  misconcep 
tion,  we  must  remember  what  has  been  already  said, 
that  by  the  analytical  treatment  of  our  concepts  the 
understanding  gains  indeed  a  great  deal,  but  the 
science  (of  metaphysics)  is  thereby  not  in  the  least 
advanced,  because  these  dissections  of  concepts  are 
nothing  but  the  materials  from  which  the  intention  is 
to  carpenter  our  science.  Let  the  concepts  of  sub 
stance  and  of  accident  be  ever  so  well  dissected  and 
determined,  all  this  is  very  well  as  a  preparation  for 
some  future  use.  But  if  we  cannot  prove,  that  in  all 
which  exists  the  substance  endures,  and  only  the  ac 
cidents  vary,  our  science  is  not  the  least  advanced 
by  all  our  analyses. 

Metaphysics  has  hitherto  never  been  able  to  prove 
a  priori  either  this  proposition,  or  that  of  sufficient 
reason,  still  less  any  more  complex  theorem,  such  as 
belongs  to  psychology  or  cosmology,  or  indeed  any 
synthetical  proposition.  By  all  its  analysing  therefore 
nothing  is  affected,  nothing  obtained  or  forwarded, 
and  the  science,  after  all  this  bustle  and  noise,  still 
remains  as  it  was  in  the  days  of  Aristotle,  though 
far  better  preparations  were  made  for  it  than  of  old, 
if  the  clue  to  synthetical  cognitions  had  only  been 
discovered. 

If  any  one  thinks  himself  offended,  he  is  at  liberty 
to  refute  my  charge  by  producing  a  single  synthetical 
proposition  belonging  to  metaphysics,  which  he  would 
prove  dogmatically  a  priori,  for  until  he  has  actually 


144  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

performed  this  feat,  I  shall  not  grant  that  he  has  truly 
advanced  the  science  ;  even  should  this  proposition  be 
sufficiently  confirmed  by  common  experience.  No  de 
mand  can  be  more  moderate  or  more  equitable,  and 
in  the  (inevitably  certain)  event  of  its  non-perform 
ance,  no  assertion  more  just,  than  that  hitherto  meta 
physics  has  never  existed  as  a  science. 

But  there  are  two  things  which,  in  case  the  chal 
lenge  be  accepted,  I  must  deprecate:  first,  trifling 
about  probability  and  conjecture,  which  are  suited  as 
little  to  metaphysics,  as  to  geometry;  and  secondly, 
a  decision  by  means  of  the  magic  wand  of  common 
sense,  which  does  not  convince  every  one,  but  which 
accommodates  itself  to  personal  peculiarities. 

For  as  to  the  former,  nothing  can  be  more  absurd, 
than  in  metaphysics,  a  philosophy  from  pure  reason 
to  think  of  grounding  our  judgments  upon  probability 
and  conjecture.  Everything  that  is  to  be  cognised  a 
priori,  is  thereby  announced  as  apodeictically  certain, 
and  must  therefore  be  proved  in  this  way.  We  might 
as  well  think  of  grounding  geometry  or  arithmetic 
upon  conjectures.  As  to  the  .doctrine  of  chances  in 
the  latter,  it  does  not  contain  probable,  but  perfectly 
certain,  judgments  concerning  the  degree  of  the  prob 
ability  of  certain  cases,  under  given  uniform  condi 
tions,  which,  in  the  sum  of  all  possible  cases,  infallibly 
happen  according  to  the  rule,  though  it  is  not  suffi 
ciently  determined  in  respect  to  every  single  chance. 
Conjectures  (by  means  of  induction  and  of  analogy) 
can  be  suffered  in  an  empirical  science  of  nature  only, 
yet  even  there  the  possibility  at  least  of  what  we  as 
sume  must  be  quite  certain. 

The  appeal  to  common  sense  is  even  more  absurd, 
when  concept  and  principles  are  announced  as  valid, 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  POSSIBLE  AS  A  SCIENCE?       145 

not  in  so  far  as  they  hold  with  regard  to  experience, 
but  even  beyond  the  conditions  of  experience.  For 
what  is  common  sense?  It  is  normal  good  sense,  so 
far  it  judges  right.  But  what  is  normal  good  sense? 
It  is  the  faculty  of  the  knowledge  and  use  of  rules  in 
concrete,  as  distinguished  from  the  speculative  under 
standing,  which  is  a  faculty  of  knowing  rules  in  ub- 
stracto.  Common  sense  can  hardly  understand  the 
rule,  "  that  every  event  is  determined  by  means  of  its 
cause,"  and  can  never  comprehend  it  thus  generally. 
It  therefore  demands  an  example  from  experience, 
and  when  it  hears  that  this  rule  means  nothing  but 
what  it  always  thought  when  a  pane  was  broken  or  a 
kitchen-utensil  missing,  it  then  understands  the  prin 
ciple  and  grants  it.  Common  sense  therefore  is  only 
of  use  so  far  as  it  can  see  its  rules  (though  they  actu 
ally  are  a  priori^)  confirmed  by  experience ;  conse 
quently  to  comprehend  them  a  priori,  or  independently 
of  experience,  belongs  to  the  speculative  understand 
ing,  and  lies  quite  beyond  the  horizon  of  common 
sense.  But  the  province  of  metaphysics  is  entirely 
confined  to  the  latter  kind  of  knowledge,  and  it  is  cer 
tainly  a  bad  index  of  common  sense  to  appeal  to  it  as 
a  witness,  for  it  cannot  here  form  any  opinion  what 
ever,  and  men  look  down  upon  it  with  contempt  until 
they  are  in  difficulties,  and  can  find  in  their  specula 
tion  neither  in  nor  out. 

It  is  a  common  subterfuge  of  those  false  friends  of 
common  sense  (who  occasionally  prize  it  highly,  but 
usually  despise  it)  to  say,  that  there  must  surely  be 
at  all  events  some  propositions  which  are  immediately 
certain,  and  of  which  there  is  no  occasion  to  give  any 
proof,  or  even  any  account  at  all,  because  we  other 
wise  could  never  stop  inquiring  into  the  grounds  of 


146  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

our  judgments  But  if  we  except  the  principle  of 
contradiction,  which  is  not  sufficient  to  show  the  truth 
of  synthetical  judgments,  they  can  never  adduce,  in 
proof  of  this  privilege,  anything  else  indubitable, 
which  they  can  immediately  ascribe  to  common  sense, 
except  mathematical  propositions,  such  as  twice  two 
make  four,  between  two  points  there  is  but  one 
straight  line,  etc.  But  these  judgments  are  radically 
different  from  those  of  metaphysics.  For  in  mathe 
matics  I  myself  can  by  thinking  construct  whatever  I 
represent  to  myself  as  possible  by  a  concept :  I  add 
to  the  first  two  the  other  two,  one  by  one,  and  myself 
make  the  number  four,  or  I  draw  in  thought  from  one 
point  to  another  all  manner  of  lines,  equal  as  well  as 
unequal ;  yet  I  can  draw  one  only,  which  is  like  itself 
in  ail  its  parts.  But  I  cannot,  by  all  my  power  of 
thinking,  extract  from  the  concept  of  a  thing  the  con 
cept  of  something  else,  whose  existence  is  necessarily 
connected  with  the  former,  but  I  must  call  in  experi 
ence.  And  though  my  understanding  furnishes  me 
a  priori  (yet  only  in  reference  to  possible  experience) 
with  the  concept  of  such  a  connexion  (i.  e.,  causation), 
I  cannot  exhibit  it,  like  the  concepts  of  mathematics, 
by  (Anschauung)  visualising  them,  a  priori,  and  so 
show  its  possibility  a  priori.  This  concept,  together 
with  the  principles  of  its  application,  always  requires, 
if  it  shall  hold  a  priori — as  is  requisite  in  metaphysics 
— a  justification  and  deduction  of  its  possibility,  be 
cause  we  cannot  otherwise  know  how  far  it  holds 
good,  and  whether  it  can  be  used  in  experience  only 
or  beyond  it  also. 

Therefore  in  metaphysics,  as  a  speculative  science 
of  pure  reason,  we  can  never  appeal  to  common  sense, 
but  may  do  so  only  v/hen  we  are  forced  to  surrender 


HOW  IS  METAPHYSICS  POSSIBLE  AS  A  SCIENCE?       147 

it,  and  to  renounce  all  purely  speculative  cognition, 
which  must  always  be  knowledge,  and  consequently 
when  we  forego  metaphysics  itself  and  its  instruction, 
for  the  sake  of  adopting  a  rational  faith  which  alone 
may  be  possible  for  us,  and  sufficient  to  our  wants, 
perhaps  even  more  salutary  than  knowledge  itself. 
For  in  this  case  the  attitude  of  the  question  is  quite 
altered.  Metaphysics  must  be  science,  not  only  as  a 
whole,  but  in  all  its  parts,  otherwise  it  is  nothing; 
because,  as  a  speculation  of  pure  reason,  it  finds  a 
hold  only  on  general  opinions.  Beyond  its  field,  how 
ever,  probability  and  common  sense  may  be  used  with 
advantage  and  justly,  but  on  quite  special  principles, 
of  which  the  importance  always  depends  on  theTefer- 
ence  to  practical  life. 

This  is  what  I  hold  myself  justified  in  requiring 
for  the  possibility  of  metaphysics  as  a  science. 


APPENDIX. 

ON    WHAT    CAN    BE    DONE    TO    MAKE    METAPHYSICS 
ACTUAL  AS  A  SCIENCE. 

SINCE  all  the  ways  heretofore  taken  have  failed  to 
attain  the  goal,  and  since  without  a  preceding 
critique  of  pure  reason  it  is  not  likely  ever  to  be  at 
tained,  the  present  essay  now  before  the  public  has  a 
fair  title  to  an  accurate  and  careful  investigation,  ex 
cept  it  be  thought  more  advisable  to  give  up  all  pre 
tensions  to  metaphysics,  to  which,  if  men  but  would 
consistently  adhere  to  their  purpose,  no  objection  can 
be  made. 

If  we  take  the  course  of  things  as  it  is,  not  as  it 
ought  to  be,  there  are  two  sorts  of  judgments:  (i)  one 
a  judgment  which  precedes  investigation  (in  our  case 
one  in  which  the  reader  from  his  own  metaphysics 
pronounces  judgment  on  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason 
which  was  intended  to  discuss  the  very  possibility  of 
metaphysics);  (2)  the  other  a  judgment  subsequent  to 
investigation.  In  the  latter  the  reader  is  enabled  to 
waive  for  awhile  the  consequences  of  the  critical 
researches  that  may  be  repugnant  to  his  formerly 
adopted  metaphysics,  and  first  examines  the  grounds 
whence  those  consequences  are  derived.  If  what 
common  metaphysics  propounds  were  demonstrably 
certain,  as  for  instance  the  theorems  of  geometry,  the 
former  way  of  judging  would  hold  good.  For  if  the 


APPENDIX.  149 

consequences  of  certain  principles  are  repugnant  to 
established  truths,  these  principles  are  false  and  with 
out  further  inquiry  to  be  repudiated.  But  if  meta 
physics  does  not  possess  a  stock  of  indisputably  cer 
tain  (synthetical)  propositions,  and  should  it  even  be 
the  case  that  there  are  a  number  of  them,  which, 
though  among  the  most  specious,  are  by  their  conse 
quences  in  mutual  collision,  and  if  no  sure  criterion 
of  the  truth  of  peculiarly  metaphysical  (synthetical) 
propositions  is  to  be  met  with  in  it,  then  the  former 
way  of  judging  is  not  admissible,  but  the  investigation 
of  the  principles  of  the  critique  must  precede  all  judg 
ments  as  to  its  value. 

ON  A  SPECIMEN  OF  A  JUDGMENT  OF  THE  CRITIQUE 
PRIOR  TO  ITS  EXAMINATION. 

This  judgment  is  to  be  found  in  the  Gottingischen ge- 
lehrten  Anzeigen,  in  the  supplement  to  the  third  divi 
sion,  of  January  19,  1782,  pages  40  et  seq. 

When  an  author  who  is  familiar  with  the  subject 
of  his  work  and  endeavors  to  present  his  independent 
reflexions  in  its  elaboration,  falls  into  the  hands  of  a 
reviewer  who,  in  his  turn,  is  keen  enough  to  discern 
the  points  on  which  the  worth  or  worthlessness  of  the 
book  rests,  who  does  not  cling  to  words,  but  goes  to 
the  heart  of  the  subject,  sifting  and  testing  more  than 
the  mere  principles  which  the  author  takes  as  his 
point  of  departure,  the  severity  of  the  judgment  may 
indeed  displease  the  latter,  but  the  public  does  not 
care,  as  it  gains  thereby;  and  the  author  himself  may 
be  contented,  as  an  opportunity  of  correcting  or  ex 
plaining  his  positions  is  afforded  to  him  at  an  early 
date  by  the  examination  of  a  competent  judge,  in 
such  a  manner,  that  if  he  believes  himself  fundamen- 


150  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

tally  right,  he  can  remove  in  time  any  stone  of  offence 
that  might  hurt  the  success  of  his  work. 

I  find  myself,  with  my  reviewer,  in  quite  another 
position.  He  seems  not  to  see  at  all  the  real  matter 
of  the  investigation  with  which  (successfully  or  un 
successfully)  I  have  been  occupied.  It  is  either  im 
patience  at  thinking  out  a  lengthy  work,  or  vexation 
at  a  threatened  reform  of  a  science  in  which  he  be 
lieved  he  had  brought  everything  to  perfection  long 
ago,  or,  what  I  am  unwilling  to  imagine,  real  narrow- 
mindedness,  that  prevents  him  from  ever  carrying  his 
thoughts  beyond  his  school-metaphysics.  In  short, 
he  passes  impatiently  in  review  a  long  series  of  prop 
ositions,  by  which,  without  knowing  their  premises, 
we  can  think  nothing,  intersperses  here  and  there  his 
censure,  the  reason  of  which  the  reader  understands 
just  as  little  as  the  propositions  against  which  it  is  di 
rected  ;  and  hence  [his  report]  can  neither  serve  the 
public  nor  damage  me,  in  the  judgment  of  experts.  I 
should,  for  these  reasons,  have  passed  over  this  judg 
ment  altogether,  were  it  not  that  it  may  afford  me  oc 
casion  for  some  explanations  which  may  in  some  cases 
save  the  readers  of  these  Prolegomena  from  a  miscon 
ception. 

In  order  to  take  a  position  from  which  my  reviewer 
could  most  easily  set  the  whole  work  in  a  most  un 
favorable  light,  without  venturing  to  trouble  himself 
with  any  special  investigation,  he  begins  and  ends  by 
saying : 

"This  work  is  a  system  of  transcendent  (or,  as  he 
translates  it,  of  higher)  Idealism."1 

IBy  no  means  "higher."  High  towers,  and  metaphysically-great  men 
resembling  them,  round  both  of  which  there  is  commonly  much  wind,  are  not 
for  me.  My  place  is  the  fruitful  bathos,  the  bottom-land,  of  experience;  and 
the  word  transcendental,  the  meaning  of  which  is  so  often  explained  by  me, 


APPENDIX.  151 

A  glance  at  this  line  soon  showed  me  the  sort  of 
criticism  that  I  had  to  expect,  much  as  though  the  re 
viewer  were  one  who  had  never  seen  or  heard  of  geom 
etry,  having  found  a  Euclid,  and  coming  upon  various 
figures  in  turning  over  its  leaves,  were  to  say,  on  being 
asked  his  opinion  of  it:  "The  work  is  a  text-book  of 
drawing  ;  the  author  introduces  a  peculiar  terminol 
ogy,  in  order  to  give  dark,  incomprehensible  direc 
tions,  which  in  the  end  teach  nothing  more  than  what 
every  one  can  effect  by  a  fair  natural  accuracy  of  eye, 
etc." 

Let  us  see,  in  the  meantime,  what  sort  of  an  ideal 
ism  it  is  that  goes  through  my  whole  work,  although 
it  does  not  by  a  long  way  constitute  the  soul  of  the 
system. 

The  dictum  of  all  genuine  idealists  from  the  Eleatic 
school  to  Bishop  Berkeley,  is  contained  in  this  for 
mula:  "All  cognition  through  the  senses  and  experi 
ence  is  nothing  but  sheer  illusion,  and  only,  in  the 
ideas  of  the  pure  understanding  and  reason  there  is 
truth." 

The  principle  that  throughout  dominates  and  de 
termines  my  Idealism,  is  on  the  contrary:  "All  cog 
nition  of  things  merely  from  pure  understanding  or 
pure  reason  is  nothing  but  sheer  illusion,  and  only  in 
experience  is  there  truth." 

But  this  is  directly  contrary  to  idealism   proper. 


but  not  once  grasped  by  my  reviewer  (so  carelessly  has  he  regarded  every 
thing),  does  not  signify  something  passing  beyond  all  experience,  but  some 
thing  that  indeed  precedes  it  a  priori,  but  that  is  intended  simply  to  make 
cognition  of  experience  possible.  If  these  conceptions  overstep  experience, 
their  employment  is  termed  transcendent,  a  word  which  must  be  distinguished 
from  transcendental,  the  latter  being  limited  to  the  immanent  use,  that  is, 
to  experience.  All  misunderstandings  of  this  kind  have  been  sufficiently 
guarded  against  in  the  work  itself,  but  my  reviewer  found  his  advantage  in 
misunderstanding  me. 


152  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

How  came  I  then  to  use  this  expression  for  quite  an 
opposite  purpose,  and  how  came  my  reviewer  to  see 
it  everywhere? 

The  solution  of  this  difficulty  rests  on  something 
that  could  have  been  very  easily  understood  from  the 
general  bearing  of  the  work,  if  the  reader  had  only 
desired  to  do  so.  Space  and  time,  together  with  all 
that  they  contain,  are  not  things  nor  qualities  in  them 
selves,  but  belong  merely  to  the  appearances  of  the 
latter:  up  to  this  point  I  am  one  in  confession  with 
the  above  idealists.  But  these,  and  amongst  them 
more  particularly  Berkeley,  regarded  space  as  a  mere 
empirical  presentation  that,  like  the  phenomenon  it 
contains,  is  only  known  to  us  by  means  of  experience 
or  perception,  together  with  its  determinations.  I, 
on  the  contrary,  prove  in  the  first  place,  that  space 
(and  also  time,  which  Berkeley  did  not  consider)  and 
all  its  determinations  a  priori,  can  be  cognised  by  us, 
because,  no  less  than  time,  it  inheres  in  our  sensibility 
as  a  pure  form  before  all  perception  or  experience  and 
makes  all  intuition  of  the  same,  and  therefore  all  its 
phenomena,  possible.  It  follows  from  this,  that  as 
truth  rests  on  universal  and  necessary  lawrs  as  its  cri 
teria,  experience,  according  to  Berkeley,  can  have  no 
criteria  of  truth,  because  its  phenomena  (according  to 
him)  have  nothing  a  priori at  their  foundation  ;  whence 
it  follows,  that  they  are  nothing  but  sheer  illusion ; 
whereas  with  us,  space  and  time  (in  conjunction  with 
the  pure  conceptions  of  the  understanding)  prescribe 
their  law  to  all  possible  experience  a  priori,  and  at 
the  same  time  afford  the  certain  criterion  for  distin 
guishing  truth  from  illusion  therein.1 

1  Idealism  proper  always  has  a  mystical  tendency,  and  can  have  no  other, 
but  mine  is  solely  designed  for  the  purpose  of  comprehending  the  possibility 


APPENDIX.  153 

My  so-called  (properly  critical)  Idealism  is  of  quite 
a  special  character,  in  that  it  subverts  the  ordinary 
idealism,  and  that  through  it  all  cognition  a  priori, 
even  that  of  geometry,  first  receives  objective  reality, 
which,  without  my  demonstrated  ideality  of  space  and 
time,  could  not  be  maintained  by  the  most  zealous 
realists.  This  being  the  state  of  the  case,  I  could 
have  wished,  in  order  to  avoid  all  misunderstanding, 
to  have  named  this  conception  of  mine  otherwise,  but 
to  alter  it  altogether  was  impossible.  It  may  be  per 
mitted  me  however,  in  future,  as  has  been  above  inti 
mated,  to  term  it  the  formal,  or  better  still,  the  crit 
ical  Idealism,  to  distinguish  it  from  the  dogmatic 
Idealism  of  Berkeley,  and  from  the  sceptical  Idealism 
of  Descartes. 

Beyond  this,  I  find  nothing  further  remarkable  in 
the  judgment  of  my  book.  The  reviewer  criticises 
here  and  there,  makes  sweeping  criticisms,  a  mode 
prudently  chosen,  since  it  does  not  betray  one's  own 
knowledge  or  ignorance  ;  a  single  thorough  criticism 
in  detail,  had  it  touched  the  main  question,  as  is  only 
fair,  would  have  exposed,  it  may  be  my  error,  or  it 
may  be  my  reviewer's  measure  of  insight  into  this  spe 
cies  of  research.  It  was,  moreover,  not  a  badly  con 
ceived  plan,  in  order  at  once  to  take  from  readers 
(who  are  accustomed  to  form  their  conceptions  of 
books  from  newspaper  reports)  the  desire  to  read  the 
book  itself,  to  pour  out  in  one  breath  a  number  of  pas 
sages  in  succession,  torn  from  their  connexion,  and 


of  our  cognition  a  priori  as  to  objects  of  experience,  which  is  a  problem 
never  hitherto  solved  or  even  suggested.  In  this  way  all  mystical  idealism 
falls  to  the  ground,  for  (as  may  be  seen  already  in  Plato)  it  inferred  from  our 
cognitions  a  priori  (even  from  those  of  geometry)  another  intuition  different 
from  that  of  the  senses  (namely,  an  intellectual  intuition),  because  it  never 
occurred  to  any  one  that  the  senses  themselves  might  intuite  a  priori. 


154  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

their  grounds  of  proof  and  explanations,  and  which 
must  necessarily  sound  senseless,  especially  consider 
ing  how  antipathetic  they  are  to  all  school-metaphys 
ics  ;  to  exhaust  the  reader's  patience  ad  nauseam,  and 
then,  after  having  made  me  acquainted  with  the  sen 
sible  proposition  that  persistent  illusion  is  truth,  to 
conclude  with  the  crude  paternal  moralisation :  to 
what  end,  then,  the  quarrel  with  accepted  language, 
to  what  end,  and  whence,  the  idealistic  distinction? 
A  judgment  which  seeks  all  that  is  characteristic  of 
my  book,  first  supposed  to  be  metaphysically  hetero 
dox,  in  a  mere  innovation  of  the  nomenclature,  proves 
clearly  that  my  would-be  judge  has  understood  noth 
ing  of  the  subject,  and  in  addition,  has  not  under 
stood  himself.1 

My  reviewer  speaks  like  a  man  who  is  conscious 
of  important  and  superior  insight  which  he  keeps  hid 
den  ;  for  I  am  aware  of  nothing  recent  with  respect  to 
metaphysics  that  could  justify  his  tone.  But  he  should 
not  withhold  his  discoveries  from  the  world,  for  there 
are  doubtless  many  who,  like  myself,  have  not  been 
able  to  find  in  all  the  fine  things  that  have  for  long 
past  been  written  in  this  department,  anything  that 
has  advanced  the  science  by  so  much  as  a  finger- 
breadth  ;  we  find  indeed  the  giving  a  new  point  to 
definitions,  the  supplying  of  lame  proofs  with  new 
crutches,  the  adding  to  the  crazy-quilt  of  metaphysics 

IThe  reviewer  often  fights  with  his  own  shadow.  When  I  oppose  the 
truth  of  experience  to  dream,  he  never  thinks  that  I  am  here  speaking  simply 
of  the  well-known  somnio  objective  sumto  of  the  Wolffian  philosophy,  which  is 
merely  formal,  and  with  which  the  distinction  between  sleeping  and  waking; 
is  in  no  way  concerned,  and  in  a  transcendental  philosophy  indeed  can  have 
no  place.  For  the  rest,  he  calls  my  deduction  of  the  categories  and  table  of 
the  principles  of  the  understanding,  "  common  well-known  axioms  of  logic 
and  ontology,  expressed  in  an  idealistic  manner."  The  reader  need  only 
consult  these  Prolegomena,  upon  this  point,  to  convince  himself  that  a  more 
miserable  and  historically  incoirtct,  judgment,  could  hardly  be  made. 


APPENDIX.  155 

fresh  patches  or  changing  its  pattern  ;  but  all  this  is 
not  what  the  world  requires.  The  world  is  tired  of 
metaphysical  assertions  ;  it  wants  the  possibility  of 
the  science,  the  sources  from  which  certainty  therein 
can  be  derived,  and  certain  criteria  by  which  it  may 
distinguish  the  dialectical  illusion  of  pure  reason  from 
truth.  To  this  the  critic  seems  to  possess  a  key,  other 
wise  he  would  never  have  spoken  out  in  such  a  high 
tone. 

But  I  am  inclined  to  suspect  that  no  such  require 
ment  of  the  science  has  ever  entered  his  thoughts,  for 
in  that  case  he  would  have  directed  his  judgment  to 
this  point,  and  even  a  mistaken  attempt  in  such  an 
important  matter,  would  have  won  his  respect.  If 
that  be  the  case,  we  are  once  more  good  friends.  He 
may  penetrate  as  deeply  as  he  likes  into  metaphysics, 
without  any  one  hindering  him  ;  only  as  concerns  that 
which  lies  outside  metaphysics,  its  sources,  which  are 
to  be  found  in  reason,  he  cannot  form  a  judgment. 
That  my  suspicion  is  not  without  foundation,  is  proved 
by  the  fact  that  he  does  not  mention  a  word  about  the 
possibility  of  synthetic  knowledge  a  priori,  the  special 
problem  upon  the  solution  of  which  the  fate  of  meta 
physics  wholly  rests,  and  upon  which  my  Critique  (as 
well  as  the  present  Prolegomena}  entirely  hinges.  The 
Idealism  he  encountered,  and  which  he  hung  upon, 
was  only  taken  up  in  the  doctrine  as  the  sole  means 
of  solving  the  above  problem  (although  it  received  its 
confirmation  on  other  grounds),  and  hence  he  must 
have  shown  either  that  the  above  problem  does  not 
possess  the  importance  I  attribute  to  it  (even  in  these 
Prolegomena},  or  that  by  my  conception  of  appear 
ances,  it  is  either  not  solved  at  all,  or  can  be  better 
solved  in  another  way ;  but  I  do  not  find  a  word  of 


156  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

this  in  the  criticism.  The  reviewer,  then,  understands 
nothing  of  my  work,  and  possibly  also  nothing  of  the 
spirit  and  essential  nature  of  metaphysics  itself;  and 
it  is  not,  what  I  would  rather  assume,  the  hurry  of  a 
man  incensed  at  the  labor  of  plodding  through  so 
many  obstacles,  that  threw  an  unfavorable  shadow 
over  the  work  lying  before  him,  and  made  its  funda 
mental  features  unrecognisable. 

There  is  a  good  deal  to  be  done  before  a  learned 
journal,  it  matters  not  with  what  care  its  writers  may 
be  selected,  can  maintain  its  otherwise  well-merited 
reputation,  in  the  field  of  metaphysics  as  elsewhere. 
Other  sciences  and  branches  of  knowledge  have  their 
standard.  Mathematics  has  it,  in  itself;  history  and 
theology,  in  profane  or  sacred  books ;  natural  science 
and  the  art  of  medicine,  in  mathematics  and  experi 
ence ;  jurisprudence,  in  law  books;  and  even  matters 
of  taste  in  the  examples  of  the  ancients.  But  for  the 
judgment  of  the  thing  called  metaphysics,  the  standard 
has  yet  to  be  found.  I  have  made  an  attempt  to  de 
termine  it,  as  well  as  its  use.  What  is  to  be  done, 
then,  until  it  be  found;  when  works  of  this  kind  have 
to  be  judged  of?  If  they  are  of  a  dogmatic  character, 
one  may  do  what  one  likes  ;  no  one  will  play  the  mas 
ter  over  others  here  for  long,  before  some  one  else 
appears  to  deal  with  him  in  the  same  manner.  If, 
however,  they  are  critical  in  their  character,  not  in 
deed  with  reference  to  other  works,  but  to  reason  it 
self,  so  that  the  standard  of  judgment  cannot  be  as 
sumed  but  has  first  of  all  to  be  sought  for,  then,  though 
objection  and  blame  may  indeed  be  permitted,  yet  a 
certain  degree  of  leniency  is  indispensable,  since  the 
need  is  common  to  us  all,  and  the  lack  of  the  neces- 


APPENDIX.  157 

sary  insight  makes  the  high-handed  attitude  of  judge 
unwarranted. 

In  order,  however,  to  connect  my  defence  with  the 
interest  of  the  philosophical  commonwealth,  I  pro 
pose  a  test,  which  must  be  decisive  as  to  the  mode, 
whereby  all  metaphysical  investigations  may  be  di 
rected  to  their  common  purpose.  This  is  nothing 
more  than  what  formerly  mathematicians  have  done, 
in  establishing  the  advantage  of  their  methods  by 
competition.  I  challenge  my  critic  to  demonstrate, 
as  is  only  just,  on  a  priori  grounds,  in  his  way,  a 
single  really  metaphysical  principle  asserted  by  him. 
Being  metaphysical  it  must  be  synthetic  and  cognised 
a  priori  from  conceptions,  but  it  may  also  be  any  one 
of  the  most  indispensable  principles,  as  for  instance, 
the  principle  of  the  persistence  of  substance,  or  of  the 
necessary  determination  of  events  in  the  world  by 
their  causes.  If  he  cannot  do  this  (silence  however  is 
confession),  he  must  admit,  that  as  metaphysics  with 
out  apodeictic  certainty  of  propositions  of  this  kind 
is  nothing  at  all,  its  possibility  or  impossibility  must 
before  all  things  be  established  in  a  critique  of  the 
pure  reason.  Thus  he  is  bound  either  to  confess  that 
my  principles  in  the  Critique  are  correct,  or  he  HI  list 
prove  their  invalidity.  But  as  I  can  already  foresee, 
that,  confidently  as  he  has  hitherto  relied  on  the  cer 
tainty  of  his  principles,  when  it  comes  to  a  strict  test 
he  will  not  find  a  single  one  in  the  whole  range  of 
metaphysics  he  can  bring  forward,  I  will  concede  to 
him  an  advantageous  condition,  which  can  only  be 
expected  in  such  a  competition,  and  will  relieve  him 
of  the  onus  probandi  by  laying  it  on  myself. 

He  finds  in  these  Prolegomena  and  in  my  Critique 
(chapter  on  the  "  Theses  and  Antitheses  of  the  Four 


158  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

Antinomies")  eight  propositions,  of  which  two  and  two 
contradict  one  another,  but  each  of  which  necessarily 
belongs  to  metaphysics,  by  which  it  must  either  be 
accepted  or  rejected  (although  there  is  not  one  that 
has  not  in  this  time  been  held  by  some  philosopher). 
Now  he  has  the  liberty  of  selecting  any  one  cf  these 
eight  propositions  at  his  pleasure,  and  accepting  it 
without  any  proof,  of  which  I  shall  make  him  a  pres 
ent,  but  only  one  (for  waste  of  time  will  be  just  as 
little  serviceable  to  him  as  to  me),  and  then  of  attack 
ing  my  proof  of  the  opposite  proposition.  If  I  can 
save  this  one,  and  at  the  same  time  show,  that  ac 
cording  to  principles  which  every  dogmatic  meta 
physics  must  necessarily  recognise,  the  opposite  of 
the  proposition  adopted  by  him  can  be  just  as  clearly 
proved,  it  is  thereby  established  that  metaphysics  has 
an  hereditary  failing,  not  to  be  explained,  much  less 
set  aside,  until  we  ascend  to  its  birth-place,  pure  rea 
son  itself,  and  thus  my  Critique  must  either  be  ac 
cepted  or  a  better  one  take  its  place;  it  must  at  least 
be  studied,  which  is  the  only  thing  I  now  require.  If, 
on  the  other  hand,  I  cannot  save  my  demonstration, 
then  a  synthetic  proposition  a  priori  from  dogmatic 
principles  is  to  be  reckoned  to  the  score  of  my  oppo 
nent,  then  also  I  will  deem  my  impeachment  of  ordi 
nary  metaphysicsas  unjust,  and  pledge  myself  to 
recognise  his  stricture  on  my  Critique  as  justified 
(although  this  would  not  be  the  consequence  by  a 
long  way).  To  this  end  it  would  be  necessary,  it 
seems  to  me,  that  he  should  step  out  of  his  incognito. 
Otherwise  I  do  not  see  how  it  could  be  avoided,  that 
instead  of  dealing  with  one,  I  should  be  honored  by 
several  problems  coming  from  anonymous  and  un 
qualified  opponents. 


APPENDIX.  159 


PROPOSALS   AS  TO  AN  INVESTIGATION  OF  THE  CRI 
TIQUE  UPON  WHICH  A  JUDGMENT  MAY  FOLLOW. 

I  feel  obliged  to  the  honored  public  even  for  the 
silence  with  which  it  for  a  long  time  favored  my  Cri 
tique,  for  this  proves  at  least  a  postponement  of  judg 
ment,  and  some  supposition  that  in  a  work,  leaving 
all  beaten  tracks  and  striking  out  on  a  new  path,  in 
which  one  cannot  at  once  perhaps  so  easily  find  one's 
way,  something  may  perchance  lie,  from  which  an 
important  but  at  present  dead  branch  of  human 
knowledge  may  derive  new  life  and  productiveness. 
Hence  may  have  originated  a  solicitude  for  the  as  yet 
tender  shoot,  lest  it  be  destroyed  by  a  hasty  judg 
ment.  A  test  of  a  judgment,  delayed  for  the  above 
reasons,  is  now  before  my  eye  in  the  Gothaischcn  gc- 
Ithrtcn  Zeitungi  the  thoroughness  of  which  every 
reader  will  himself  perceive,  from  the  clear  and  un- 
perverted  presentation  of  a  fragment  of  one  of  the 
first  principles  of  my  work,  without  taking  into  con 
sideration  my  own  suspicious  praise. 

And  now  I  propose,  since  an  extensive  structure 
cannot  be  judged  of  as  a  whole  from  a  hurried  glance, 
to  test  it  piece  by  piece  from  its  foundations,  so  thereby 
the  present  Prolegomena  may  fitly  be  used  as  a  gene 
ral  outline  with  which  the  work  itself  may  occasionally 
be  compared.  This  notion,  if  it  were  founded  on 
nothing  more  than  my  conceit  of  importance,  such  as 
vanity  commonly  attributes  to  one's  own  productions, 
would  be  immodest  and  would  deserve  to  be  repudi 
ated  with  disgust.  But  now,  the  interests  of  specula 
tive  philosophy  have  arrived  at  the  point  of  total  ex 
tinction,  while  human  reason  hangs  upon  them  with 


160  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

inextinguishable  affection,  and  only  after  having  been 
ceaselessly  deceived  does  it  vainly  attempt  to  change 
this  into  indifference. 

In  our  thinking  age  it  is  not  to  be  supposed  but 
that  many  deserving  men  would  use  any  good  oppor 
tunity  of  working  for  the  common  interest  of  the  more 
and  more  enlightened  reason,  if  there  were  only  some 
hope  of  attaining  the  goal.  Mathematics,  natural 
science,  laws,  arts,  even  morality,  etc.,  do  not  com 
pletely  fill  the  soul ;  there  is  always  a  space  left  over, 
reserved  for  pure  and  speculative  reason,  the  vacuity 
of  which  prompts  us  to  seek  in  vagaries,  buffooneries, 
and  myticism  for  what  seems  to  be  employment  and 
entertainment,  but  what  actually  is  mere  pastime;  in 
order  to  deaden  the  troublesome  voice  of  reason, 
which  in  accordance  with  its  nature  requires  some 
thing  that  can  satisfy  it,  and  not  merely  subserve 
other  ends  or  the  interests  of  our  inclinations.  A  con 
sideration,  therefore,  which  is  concerned  only  with 
reason  as  it  exists  for  it  itself,  has  as  I  may  reason 
ably  suppose  a  great  fascination  for  every  one  who 
has  attempted  thus  to  extend  his  conceptions,  and  I 
may  even  say  a  greater  than  any  other  theoretical 
branch  of  knowledge,  for  which  he  would  not  willingly 
exchange  it,  because  here  all  other  cognitions,  and 
even  purposes,  must  meet  and  unite  themselves  in  a 
whole. 

I  offer,  therefore,  these  Prolegomena  as  a  sketch 
and  text-book  for  this  investigation,  and  not  the  work 
itself.  Although  I  am  even  now  perfectly  satisfied 
with  the  latter  as  far  as  contents,  order,  and  mode  of 
presentation,  and  the  care  that  I  have  expended  in 
weighing  and  testing  every  sentence  before  writing  it 
down,  are  concerned  (for  it  has  taken  me  years  to 


APPENDIX.  l6l 

satisfy  myself  fully,  not  only  as  regards  the  whole, 
but  in  some  cases  even  as  to  the  sources  of  one  par 
ticular  proposition);  yet  I  am  not  quite  satisfied  with 
my  exposition  in  some  sections  of  the  doctrine  of  ele 
ments,  as  for  instance  in  the  deduction  of  the  concep 
tions  of  the  Understanding,  or  in  that  on  the  paral 
ogisms  of  pure  reason,  because  a  certain  diffuseness 
takes  away  from  their  clearness,  and  in  place  of  them, 
what  is  here  said  in  the  Prolegomena  respecting  these 
sections,  may  be  made  the  basis  of  the  test. 

It  is  the  boast  of  the  Germans  that  where  steady 
and  continuous  industry  are  requisite,  they  can  carry 
things  farther  than  other  nations.  If  this  opinion  be 
well  founded,  an  opportunity,  a  business,  presents  it 
self,  the  successful  issue  of  which  we  can  scarcely 
doubt,  and  in  which  all  thinking  men  can  equally 
take  part,  though  they  have  hitherto  been  unsuccess 
ful  in  accomplishing  it  and  in  thus  confirming  the 
above  good  opinion.  But  this  is  chiefly  because  the 
science  in  question  is  of  so  peculiar  a  kind,  that  it 
can  be  at  once  brought  to  completion  and  to  that  en 
during  state  that  it  will  never  be  able  to  be  brought 
in  the  least  degree  farther  or  increased  by  later  dis 
coveries,  or  even  changed  (leaving  here  out  of  account 
adornment  by  greater  clearness  in  some  places,  or 
additional  uses),  and  this  is  an  advantage  no  other 
science  has  or  can  have,  because  there  is  none  so  fully 
isolated  and  independent  of  others,  and  which  is  con 
cerned  with  the  faculty  of  cognition  pure  and  simple. 
And  the  present  moment  seems,  moreover,  not  to  be 
unfavorable  to  my  expectation,  for  just  now,  in  Ger 
many,  no  one  seems  to  know  wherewith  to  occupy 
himself,  apart  from  the  so-called  useful  sciences,  so 


162  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

as  to  pursue  not  mere  play,  but  a  business  possessing 
an  enduring  purpose. 

To  discover  the  means  how  the  endeavors  of  the 
learned  may  be  united  in  such  a  purpose,  I  must  leave 
to  others.  In  the  meantime,  it  is  my  intention  to  per 
suade  any  one  merely  to  follow  my  propositions,  or 
even  to  flatter  me  with  the  hope  that  he  will  do  so ; 
but  attacks,  repetitions,  limitations,  or  confirmation, 
completion,  and  extension,  as  the  case  may  be,  should 
be  appended.  If  the  matter  be  but  investigated  from 
its  foundation,  it  cannot  fail  that  a  system,  albeit  not 
my  own,  shall  be  erected,  that  shall  be  a  possession 
for  future  generations  for  which  they  may  have  reason 
to  be  grateful. 

It  would  lead  us  too  far  here  to  show  what  kind  of 
metaphysics  may  be  expected,  when  only  the  princi 
ples  of  criticism  have  been  perfected,  and  how,  be 
cause  the  old  false  feathers  have  been  pulled  out,  she 
need  by  no  means  appear  poor  and  reduced  to  an  in 
significant  figure,  but  may  be  in  other  respects  richly 
and  respectably  adorned.  But  other  and  great  uses 
which  would  result  from  such  a  reform,  strike  one  im 
mediately.  The  ordinary  metaphysics  had  its  uses, 
in  tnat  it  sought  out  the  elementary  conceptions  of 
the  pure  understanding  in  order  to  make  them  clear 
through  analysis,  and  definite  by  explanation.  In  this 
way  it  was  a  training  for  reason,  in  whatever  direction 
it  might  be  turned;  but  this  was  all  the  good  it  did; 
service  was  subsequently  effaced  when  it  favored  con 
ceit  by  venturesome  assertions,  sophistry  by  subtle 
distinctions  and  adornment,  and  shallowness  by  the 
ease  with  which  it  decided  the  most  difficult  problems 
by  means  of  a  little  school-wisdom,  which  is  only  the 
more  seductive  the  more  it  has  the  choice,  on  the  one 


APPENDIX.  163 

hand,  of  taking  something  from  the  language  of  sci 
ence,  and  on  the  other  from  that  of  popular  discourse, 
thus  being  everything  to  everybody,  but  in  reality 
nothing  at  all.  By  criticism,  however,  a  standard  is 
given  to  our  judgment,  whereby  knowledge  may  be 
with  certainty  distinguished  from  pseudo-science,  and 
firmly  founded,  being  brought  into  full  operation  in 
metaphysics  ;  a  mode  of  thought  extending  by  degrees 
its  beneficial  influence  over  every  other  use  of  reason, 
at  once  infusing  into  it  the  true  philosophical  spirit. 
But  the  service  also  that  metaphysics  performs  for 
theology,  by  making  it  independent  of  the  judgment 
of  dogmatic  speculation,  thereby  assuring  it  com 
pletely  against  the  attacks  of  all  such  opponents,  is 
certainly  not  to  be  valued  lightly.  For  ordinary  meta 
physics,  although  it  promised  the  latter  much  advan 
tage,  could  not  keep  this  promise,  and  moreover,  by 
summoning  speculative  dogmatics  to  its  assistance, 
did  nothing  but  arm  enemies  against  itself.  Mysti 
cism,  which  can  prosper  in  a  rationalistic  age  only 
when  it  hides  itself  behind  a  system  of  school-meta 
physics,  under  the  protection  of  which  it  may  venture 
to  rave  with  a  semblance  of  rationality,  is  driven  from 
this,  its  last  hiding-place,  by  critical  philosophy.  Last, 
but  not  least,  it  cannot  be  otherwise  than  important 
to  a  teacher  of  metaphysics,  to  be  able  to  say  with 
universal  assent,  that  what  he  expounds  is  Science, 
and  that  thereby  genuine  services  will  be  rendered  to 
the  commonweal. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY, 

BY  DR.  PAUL  CARUS. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

T)HILOSOPHY  is  frequently  regarded  as  idle  ver- 
L  biage  ;  and  the  great  mass  of  the  average  produc 
tions  of  this  branch  of  human  endeavor  would  seem 
to  justify  the  statement.  Nevertheless,  philosophy 
has  exercised  a  paramount  influence  upon  the  history 
of  mankind,  for  philosophy  is  the  quintessence  of 
man's  conception  of  the  world  and  the  view  he  takes 
of  the  significance  of  life.  While  philosophical  books, 
essays,  lectures,  and  lessons  may  be  intricate  and  long- 
winded,  there  is  at  the  core  of  all  the  questions  under 
discussion  a  public  interest  of  a  practical  nature.  The 
problems  that  have  reference  to  it  are,  as  a  rule,  much 
simpler  and  of  more  common  application  than  is  ap 
parent  to  an  outsider,  and  all  of  them  closely  consid 
ered  will  be  found  to  be  of  a  religious  nature. 

KANT'S  SIGNIFICANCE  IN  THE  HISTORY  OF 
PHILOSOPHY. 

When  we  try  to  trace  the  erratic  lines  of  the  his 
tory  of  philosophy,  the  advance  seems  slow,  but  the 
results,  meagre  though  they  sometimes  may  be,  can 
be  summarised  in  brief  statements.  Thus  the  sophistic 
movement  in  Greece  in  contradistinction  to  the  old 
naive  naturalists,  Thales,  Anaximander,  and  Anaxi- 
menes,  is  characterised  by  the  maxim  :  iraimoi/  fierpoi/ 
m>0pawros,  [Man  is  the  measure  of  all  things],  which  is 
the  simple  solution  of  a  series  of  intricate  problems. 


168  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

In  spite  of  its  truth,  it  was  misused  by  unscrupulous 
rhetoricians,  who  disgraced  the  profession  of  sophists 
and  degraded  the  noble  name  of  their  science,  called 
Sophia,  i.  e.,  wisdom,  to  such  an  extent  that  the  term 
'  < sophist "  became  an  epithet  of  opprobrium.  Socrates 
Opposed  the  sophists,  but  in  all  theoretical  points  he 
Vvas  one  ol  them.  There  was  only  this  difference, 
that  he  insisted  on  the  moral  nature  of  man  and  thus 
became  the  noblest  exponent  of  the  sophistic  prin 
ciple.  It  indicates  a  new  departure  that  he  changed 
the  name  sophia  to  philosophia  or  philosophy,  i.  e.,  love 
of  wisdom,  which  was  universally  accepted  as  more 
modest  and  better  becoming  to  the  teachers  and  spir 
itual  guides  of  mankind.  While  he  granted  that  man 
is  the  measure  of  all  things,  he  pointed  out  the  duty 
of  investigating  the  nature  of  man,  and  he  selected 
the  Delphic  maxim  :  yv&Qi  o-tavrov,  "know  thyself,"  as 
a  motto  for  his  life.  It  would  lead  us  too  far  to  show 
how  Plato  worked  out  the  Socratic  problem  of  the  hu 
man  soul,  which  led  him  to  a  recognition  of  the  sig 
nificance  of  forms,  as  expressed  in  his  doctrine  of 
ideas,  and  how  Aristotle  applied  it  to  natural  science. 
The  Neo-Platonists  developed  Plato's  mystical  and 
supernatural  tendencies  and  prepared  thereby  for  the 
rise  of  a  dualistic  religion. 

When  Christianity  became  a  dominating  power  in 
the  world,  philosophy  disappeared  for  a  while,  being 
replaced  by  the  belief  in  a  divine  revelation  as  the 
sole  source  of  all  wisdom ;  but  in  the  Middle  Ages 
philosophy  was  revived  as  scholasticism,  the  impulse 
to  the  movement  being  due  to  the  revival  of  Aristote- 
lianism,  through  an  acquaintance  with  the  writings  of 
cultured  Arabian  sages. 

In  the  era  of  scholasticism  we  have  two  authori- 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  169 

ties,  Revelation  and  Science,  the  former  conceived  to 
be  identical  with  the  verdicts  of  the  Church,  the  latter 
being  a  blind  acceptance  of  a  second-hand  and  much 
distorted"  knowledge  of  the  philosopher's  works.  The 
Platonic  problem  of  the  eternal  types  of  things  was 
revived,  and  Nominalists  and  Realists  contended  with 
one  another  on  the  question  of  the  reality  of  ideas.  In 
their  methods,  however,  these  two  conflicting  schools 
were  on  the  same  level,  for  both  were  in  the  habit  of 
appealing  to  certain  authorities.  With  them  proof 
consisted  in  quotations  either  of  church  doctrines  or 
of  passages  from  Aristotle.  There  was  no  genuine 
science,  no  true  philosophy,  the  efforts  of  the  age 
consisting  in  vain  attempts  at  reconciling  the  two 
conflicting  sources  of  their  opinions. 

Modern  philosophy  is  a  product  of  the  awakening 
spirit  of  science,  beginning  with  Descartes  who  pro 
posed  to  introduce  method  into  philosophy,  as  ex 
pressed  in  his  Discourse  on  Method.  He  abolished  the 
implicit  belief  in  book  authority.  Falling  back  upon 
the  facts  of  life,  he  bethought  himself  of  the  signifi 
cance  of  Man's  thinking  faculty,  and  so,  starting  again 
from  the  subjective  position  of  the  sophists,  he  defined 
his  solution  of  the  basic  problem  with  great  terseness 
in  the  sentence  :  Cogito  ergo  sum,  [I  think,  therefore 
I  am]. 

The  latest  phase  in  philosophy  begins  with  Kant, 
and  it  is  his  immortal  merit  to  have  gone  to  the  bot 
tom  of  the  philosophical  problem  by  reducing  its  diffi 
culties  to  a  system.  In  the  Cartesian  syllogism  he 
saw  a  fallacy  if  it  was  interpreted  to  mean  "Cogito 
ergo  ego  sum. " 

The  subject  ego,  implied  in  "sum"  is  implicitly 
contained  in  " cogito,"  and  thus  if  the  sentence  is 


170  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

meant  to  prove  the  existence  of  a  metaphysical  ego, 
the  argument  is  a  fallacy,  being  merely  a  deduction 
derived  from  the  assumption  that  the  ego  does  the 
thinking. 

In  spite  of  its  syllogistic  form  the  sentence  was 
not  meant  as  a  syllogism  but  as  a  statement  of  fact. 
Kant's  objection,  however,  holds  good  in  either  case, 
for  though  the  thinking  be  a  fact,  it  is  an  assumption 
to  take  for  granted  that  the  thinker  is  an  ego,  i.  e.,  a 
soul-entity  that  exists  independently  of  its  thinking. 
Lichtenberg  therefore  said  that  we  ought  to  replace 
the  sentence  "/  think"  by  "it  thinks."  Yet  even  if 
we  allow  the  statement  " I  think"  to  pass,  the  ques 
tion  arises  :  What  do  we  understand  by  "/"?  Is  it  a 
collective  term  for  all  the  thought-processes  that  take 
place  in  one  and  the  same  personality,  or  is  there  a 
separate  soul-being  which  does  the  thinking  and  con 
stitutes  the  personality?  In  other  words,  the  exist 
ence  of  the  thinking  subject,  called  the  /,  does  riot 
imply  that  it  is  a  spiritual  thing  in  itself,  nor  even 
that  it  constitutes  a  unity. 

Mystic  tendencies  of  a  religious  nature  such  as 
found  a  classical  exposition  in  Kant's  contemporary 
and  namesake,  Emanuel  Swedenborg,  rendered  some 
of  the  problems  of  philosophy  more  complicated  by 
laying  special  stress  upon  the  difference  between  mat 
ter  and  spirit,  and  discussing  the  possibility  and  prob 
able  nature  of  purely  spiritual  beings;  but  all  philoso 
phising  on  the  subject  consisted  in  declamations  and 
unproved  propositions. 

Wolf,  a  clear-headed  thinker,  though  void  of  origi 
nality,  reduced  the  metaphysical  notions  from  Aris 
totle  down  to  the  eighteenth  century  into  an  elaborate 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  171 

system,  and  thus  became  to  Kant  the  typical  exponent 
of  dogmatism. 

In  contrast  to  the  metaphysical  school,  the  sen 
sualists  had  risen.  They  are  best  represented  by 
Locke  who  denied  the  existence  of  innate  ideas  (ex 
cept  the  idea  of  causation)  and  tried  to  prove  that  all 
abstract  thought  had  its  origin  in  sensation.  Hume, 
taking  offence  even  at  the  claims  of  causation  as  a 
necessary  connexion,  declared  that,  accustomed  to 
the  invariable  sequence  of  cause  and  effect,  we  mis 
take  our  subjective  necessity  of  thinking  them  to 
gether  for  an  objective  necessity,  which  remains  un 
proved.  Thus  he  turned  skeptic  and  gave  by  his 
doubts  regarding  the  objective  validity  of  causation 
as  a  universal  principle  and  a  metaphysical  truth  the 
suggestion  to  Kant  to  investigate  the  claims  of  all 
metaphysics,  of  which  the  notion  of  causality  is  only 
a  part. 

Here  Kant's  philosophical  reform  set  in,  which 
consists  in  rejecting  both  the  skepticism  of  Hume  and 
the  dogmatism  of  Wolf  and  in  offering  a  new  solution 
which  he  called  criticism. 

Kant  took  the  next  step  in  seeking  for  the  prin 
ciple  that  determined  all  thinking,  and  discovered  it 
in  the  purely  formal  laws  of  thought,  which  in  their 
complete  unity  constitute  pure  reason.  The  investi 
gation  of  the  conditions  of  thought,  he  called  "criti 
cism."  He  insisted  that  the  dogmatical  declamations 
of  all  the  various  systems  of  metaphysics  were  idle 
and  useless  talk.  He  said  they  were  vain  attempts  at 
building  a  mighty  tower  that  would  reach  to  Heaven. 
But  at  the  same  time  he  claimed  to  prove  that  the 
supply  of  building  materials  was  after  all  sufficient  for 


172  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

a  dwelling-house  spacious  enough  for  the  needs  of  life 
aud  high  enough  to  survey  the  field  of  experience.1 

In  place  of  the  old  metaphysics  which  used  to  de 
rive  from  pure  concepts  a  considerable  amount  of 
pretended  knowledge  concerning  God,  the  world,  and 
man,  concerning  substance,  as  the  substratum  of  ex 
istence,  the  soul,  the  future  state  of  things,  and  im 
mortality,  Kant  drew  up  an  inventory  of  the  posses 
sions  of  Pure  Reason  and  came  to  the  conclusion  that 
all  knowledge  of  purely  formal  thought  is  in  itself 
empty  and  that  sense-experience  in  itself  is  blind  ;  the 
two  combined  form  the  warp  and  woof  of  experience, 
which  alone  can  afford  positive  information  concern 
ing  the  nature  of  objects.  Empirical  knowledge  of 
the  senses  furnishes  the  material,  while  formal  thought 
supplies  the  method  by  which  perceptions  can  be  or 
ganised  and  systematised  into  knowledge.  Kant's  aim 
was  not  to  produce  glittering  generalities,  but  to  offer 
critique,  that  is  to  say,  a  method  of,  and  norm  for, 
scientific  thought ;  and  he  said,  conscious  of  the  sig 
nificance  of  his  philosophy: 

"This  much  is  certain,  that  whoever  has  once  tasted  critique 
will  be  ever  after  disgusted  with  all  dogmatical  twaddle." 

Dogmatism  in  metaphysics  is  the  dragon  which 
Kant  slew.  But  Kant's  criticism  was  not  purely  nega 
tive.  He  recognised  in  the  world  as  an  undeniable 
fact  the  demand  of  the  moral  "ought"  which  he  called 
"the  categorical  imperative,"  and  while  he  insisted 
upon  the  determinism  of  natural  law  he  would  not 
deny  the  freedom  of  the  will  establishing  it  upon 


1  See  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  in  the  chapter  "Transcendental  Doctrine  ol 
Method,"  Max  Mullet's  translation,  p.  567,  Meicklejohn's,  p.  431,  original 
edition,  p.  707. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  173 

man's  moral  responsibility.      He  declared  :    "I  shall, 
therefore  I  can." 


PERSONAL  TRAITS. 

Kant,  the  son  of  simple  but  rigorously  pious  parents 
of  Scotch  extraction,  lived  at  Konigsberg  in  Prus 
sia  under  the  rule  of  Frederick  the  Great.1  His  moral 
sense  was  stern  and  unalloyed  with  sentimentality. 
He  never  married,  and  his  relation  to  his  relatives 
was  regulated  strictly  according  to  his  views  of  duty.2 
In  his  philosophy  as  well  as  in  his  private  life  he  was 
duty  incarnate.  While  he  had  imbibed  the  sense  of 
duty  that  characterises  the  system  of  education  in 
Prussia,  he  was  also  swayed  by  the  ideals  of  liberty 
and  fraternity  so  vigorously  brought  to  the  front  by 
the  French  revolution.8  His  influence  on  the  German 
nation,  on  science,  religion,  and  even  politics  cannot 
be  underrated,  although  his  ideas  did  not  reach  the 
people  directly  in  the  form  he  uttered  them,  but  only 
indirectly  through  his  disciples,  the  preachers,  teach 
ers,  and  poets  of  the  age.  His  main  works  which  em 
body  the  gist  of  his  peculiar  doctrines  are  the  Critique 
of  Pure  Reason,  the  Critique  of  Practical  Reason,  and 
the  Critique  of  Judgment.  Among  them  the  Critique 

IFor  a  good  condensed  statement  of  Kant's  life  see  page  245  of  this  vol 
ume,  where  Professor  Windelband's  account  is  reproduced.  For  a  convenient 
chronological  table  of  the  data  of  Kant's  life  and  publications  see  pages  287- 
291  of  the  present  volume. 


have  had  reproduced  at  p.  285  of  this  volume  a  specimen  of  Kant's 
handwriting,  a  letter  of  his  to  his  brother,  plainly  characterising  his  business 
like  conception  of  duty  which  regulated  his  life  with  machine-like  preci 
sion. 

SHeinrich  Heine  described  Kant  to  the  French  most  drastically  in  an 
essay  on  German  philosophy,  of  which  an  English  translation  has  been  re 
printed  in  this  volume  at  page  264. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  175 

of  Pure  Reason  is  by  far  the  most  important  one.1  It 
is  a  pity  that  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason,  from  the 
appearance  of  which  the  historian  dates  the  beginning 
of  the  latest  period  in  the  evolution  of  philosophy,  is 
a  ponderous  and  almost  unintelligible  work, — a  book 
with  seven  seals  to  the  average  reader;  and  it  might 
have  remained  ineffectual  had  not  Kant  been  necessi 
tated  to  rectify  this  defect  by  giving  to  the  public  a 
popular  explanation  concerning  his  intentions. 

The  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  was  published  in  1781. 
In  the  Gottingenschen  Gelehrten  Anzeigen  of  January 
19,  1782,  there  appeared  a  review  of  the  book,  written 
by  Garve  and  modified  by  Feder,  which  irritated  Kant 
considerably,  because  the  review  treated  his  criticism 
as  a  revival  of  Berkeley's  idealism,  which  was  com 
monly  regarded  as  pure  subjectivism.2  There  is  no 
need  here  of  protesting  in  Berkeley's  name  against 
this  interpretation  of  his  philosophy,  for  we  are  con 
cerned  here  with  Kant,  not  with  Berkeley.  But  even 
Kant  misunderstood  Berkeley,8  and  for  our  present 

1  A  splendid  analysis  of  the  three  Critiques  is  given  by  Prof.  A.  Weber  in 
his  History  of  Philosophy,  translated  from  the  fifth  French  edition  by  Prof. 
Frank  Tilly,  pp.  436-472.  We  have  reprinted  part  of  this  analysis  at  p.  250. 

The  compilation  of  Kant's  philosophy  in  a  Kantlexikon  by  Gustav  Wegner 
(Berlin,  1893)  is  not  very  serviceable.  The  book  is  unhandy  and  lacks  the 
main  requisite  of  a  lexicon,  a  good  index. 

The  exposition  of  Kant's  philosophy  by  G.  H.  Lewes  in  his  Biographical 
History  of  Philosophy  is  an  excellent  sketch  and  worth  a  careful  perusal.  But 
Lewes  leaves  the  problem  where  Kant  left  it,  saying  :  "There  is,  in  truth,  no 
necessity  in  causation,  except  the  necessity  of  our  belief  in  it."  But  whence 
does  this  necessity  come,  and  what  is  its  authority  ? 

5  Garve' s  letter  to  Kant  and  Kant's  answer  contain  the  whole  material  of 
the  history  of  this  garbled  review.  They  are  interesting  reading  but  mainly 
of  a  personal  nature,  consisting  of  explanations,  excuses,  and  polite  words. 
For  a  reproduction  of  this  correspondence  see  Reclaim's  text  edition  of  Kant's 
Prolegomena,  Appendix,  pp.  214-230. 

'For  a  condensed  statement  of  Berkeley's  idealism  see  Thomas  J.  Mc- 
Cormack's  preface  to  Berkeley's  Treatise  Concerning  the  Principle*  ef  Human 
Knowledge,  Chicago,  The  Open  Court  Pub.  Co.,  1901,  especially  pp.  XU-KIT. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 


purpose  it  is  sufficient  to  say  that  Berkeley's  idealism 
meant  to  Kant  and  bis  contemporaries  pure  subjec 
tivism. 

Kant  was  irritated  because  his  philosophy  was  dis 


posed  of  as  an  old  error,  a  method  which  (as  P^ulsen 
says)  has  been  developed  into  a  regular  system  among 
a  certain  class  of  Roman  Catholic  critics  who  regard 
{lie  possibilities  of  philosophising  as.  exhausted  ir/  ihe 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  177 

history  of  philosophy.  Claiming  to  be  in  possession 
of  the  whole  truth,  they  are  naturally  disinclined  to 
believe  that  new  truths  can  be  brought  to  light.  Thus 
they  have  developed  the  habit  of  associating  every 
new  idea  with  some  one  of  the  systems  of  the  past 
which  to  them  are  nothing  but  a  catalogus  errorum, 
and  serve  them  as  so  many  coffins  in  which  to  bury 
any  doctrine  that  does  not  receive  their  approbation. 

Kant's  indignation  was  perhaps  exaggerated,  for 
he  ought  to  have  considered  the  difficulty  of  under 
standing  a  doctrine  that  was  at  the  same  time  utterly 
new  and  presented  in  a  most  unattractive,  pedantical 
form ;  but  the  result  was  happy,  for  he  felt  urged  to 
write  a  popular  explanation  of  his  work,  to  offset 
Garve's  misconception,  which  would  serve  the  reader 
as  Prolegomena,  i.  e  ,  as  prefatory  remarks  to  the  Cri 
tique  of  Pure  Reason. 

These  Prolegomena  insist  on  the  newness  of  Kant's 
proposition  and  emphasise  his  adhesion  to  realism  (or 
the  doctrine  that  the  objective  world  is  actual)  in  con 
trast  to  the  subjectivism  of  Berkeley,  or  what  was  sup 
posed  to  be  Berkeley.  At  the  same  time  they  possess 
the  charm  of  wonderful  vigor  and  directness.  Here 
Kant  does  not  write  in  the  pedantic,  dignified  style 
of  a  professor,  but  with  the  boldness  of  a  resentful 
author  who,  conscious  of  his  title  to  careful  considera 
tion  and  believing  himself  to  be  wrongly  criticised,  is 
anxious  to  be  properly  understood  by  the  public. 

While  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  is  synthetic,  the 
Prolegomena  are  (as  says  Kant  himself)  analytic.  In 
the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  Kant  discourses  as  one 
who  speaks  ex  cathedra,  sitting  in  the  professorial 
chair;  he  propounds  his  doctrine  deductively,  and  I 

1  See  Friedrich  Paulsen's  Kant,  p.  229. 


tjS  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

for  one  can  very  well  understand  that  his  expositions 
appear  to  an  uninitiated  reader  bewilderingly  orac 
ular.  In  the  Prolegomena  his  style  is  not  stilted  but 
rather  careless  and  though  his  periods  are  long  they 
are  fluent  and  easily  understood. 

KANT'S  TERMS. 

The  main  difficulty  of  understanding  Kant,  to  later 
generations,  and  also  to  foreigners  not  to  the  manner 
born  as  regards  the  German  vernacular,  lies  in  his 
terminology.  Simple  though  his  terms  are  when  once 
understood,  they  afford  unsurmountable  difficulties  to 
those  who  are  not  familiar  with  their  significance. 

Familiarity  with  the  following  terms  is  indispen 
sable  for  a  comprehension  of  Kant:  " metaphysics "; 
''understanding"  and  "reason";  "empirical"  and 
"experience";  "noumenon"  and  " phenomenon "; 
a  priori  and  a  posteriori',  "transcendental"  and  "tran 
scendent"  ;  and  "intuition"  or  Anschauung. 

First,  above  all,  there  is  the  term  "metaphysics," 
which  is  the  science  of  first  principles.  Aristotle,  who 
discusses  the  subject  of  ap\ai,  or  first  principles,  in 
books  placed  after  the  physical  treatises  (hence  the 
name  ra  /nera  ra  <£v<ri*a,  sc.  f!t/3\ia,  corrupted  into  meta 
physics),  calls  it  First  Philosophy,  i.  e.,  the  Essence 
or  basis  of  Philosophy,  and  identifies  it  with  Theol 
ogy,  because  he  finds  in  God  the  ultimate  raison  d'etre 
of  all  metaphysical  concepts  such  as  being  and  be 
coming,  space  and  time,  multiplicity  and  unity,  things 
and  the  world,  cause  and  effect,  substance  and  qual 
ity,  God  and  soul  and  immortality. 

Kant  defines  metaphysics  as : 

"A  system  of  all  the  principles  of  pure  theo 
retical   reason-cognition  (  Vernunfttrkenntniss)   in 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  179 

concepts, — briefly  the  system  of  pure  theoretical 
philosophy."  l 

In    another   place    Kant    (IV.,  p.  236)   speaks    of 
metaphysics  simply  as  "pure  philosophy  limited  to 
the  objects  of  the  understanding,"  a  definition  which 
almost  identifies  it  with  Logic.2  He  insists  that  meta 
physics  is  based  upon  man's  faculty  of  thinking  and 
not  pure  imagination.     Being  a  priori,  it  deals  witli^ 
the  acts  of  pure  thought,  which  reduce  the  manifold  j 
sense-impressions  to  unity  bylaw.   (Vol.  IV.,  p.  362.) 

The  sources  of  metaphysics  are  limited  by  Kant 
to  the  a  priori  (Vol.  IV.,  p.  13);  its  possibility  stands 
and  falls  with  the  possibility  of  synthetical  judgments 
a  priori  (Vol.  IV.,  p.  14);  pre-Kantian  metaphysics 
is  declared  to  be  uncritical  and  unscientific  (IV.,  p. 
23);  as  a  science  metaphysics  must  be  a  systematic 
presentation  of  all  a  priori  concepts,  including  above 
all  the  synthetical  propositions  of  man's  philosophical 
cognition;  and  its  final  purpose  (IV.,  p.  19)  consists 
in  the  cognition  of  the  Supreme  Being  as  well  as  of 
the  life  to  come  (die  zukiinftige  Welt}.  The  latter 
expression  had  perhaps  better  be  replaced  by  the 
broader  idea  of  the  mundus  intelligibility  the  intelligible 
world,  constituting  the  purely  formal  in  contrast  to 
the  material,  the  Platonic  ideas  or  types  of  things  as 
distinguished  from  their  accidental  relations  in  space 
and  time,  exhibiting  the  abiding  in  the  transcient  and 
thus  making  it  possible  to  view  the  world  (as  Spinoza 
has  it)  under  the  aspect  of  eternity, — sub  specie  ceterni. 

Kant  started  a  new  line  of  investigation  and  kept 
in  view  his  main  aim.  So  it  was  natural  that  he  did 

l£d.  Hartenstein,  Vol.  VIII.,  p.  521. 

2  Logic  is  defined  by  Kant  (IV.,  p.  236)  as  "  the  pure  philosophy  which  is 
purely  formal." 


i8o  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

not  feel  the  need  of  certain  discriminations  before  his 
work  was  pretty  well  advanced.  This  accounts  for  a 
few  inaccuracies  in  the  use  of  his  terminology,  cover 
ing  the  terms  "understanding,"  "reason,"  and  "ex 
perience."  He  distinguishes  in  his  Prolegomena  be 
tween  reason  and  understanding,  but  the  discrimination 
is  by  no  means  thoroughly  carried  out.  Theunder- 
standing  is  defined  as  the  use  of  the  categories,  and 
reason  tne  taculty  ot  forming  ideas^  The  understand- 
in  g~liZc^r^in^TyTe^re^ntsthe  logical  functions,  and 
reason  the  domain  of  abstractions  and  generalisations. 
The  understanding  draws  conclusions  and  attends  to 
the  machinery  of  thinking,  reason  seeks  oneness  in 
plurality,  aims  at  a  systematical  comprehension  of 
things  apparently  different  and  establishes  laws  to  ex 
plain  the  variety  of  phenomena  by  one  common  rule. 

By  "empirical"  Kant  understood  all  those  judg 
ments  that  contain  sensory  elements.  They  were  either 
mereTperceptions,  i.  e.,  a  taking  cognisance  of  sense- 
impressions,  or  experience,  i.  e. ,  the  product  of 
thought  and  perceptions,  resulting  in  empirical  state 
ments  that  are  universally  valid.1 

The  contrast  of  perceptions,  as  the  sense-woven 
pictures  of  things,  and  ideas  or  the  mind-begotten 
concepts  of  them,  is  expressed  in  the  two  terms 
"phenomenon"  or  appearance,  and  "noumenon"  or 
thought.  Kant  translates  the  former  by  the  word  Sin- 
neswesen,  i.  e. ,  creature  of  the  senses,  and  the  latter 
by  the  word  Gedankcnwescn,  i.  e.,  creature  of  thought.2 

1  That  Kant' s  use  of  the  term  "  experience  "  was  not  always  consistent  I 
have  endeavored  to  explain  elsewhere.     See  Printer  of  Philosophy,  pp.  30  ft. 

2  Pronounce  no-comenon%  not  noomenon.     The  original  Greek  reads  voov- 
ficpov.  The  ou  in  the  German  transcription,  "No-umetton  "  was  misinterpreted 
as  a  French  ou;  hence  the  erroneous  pronunciation  of  some  English  lexicog 
raphers  as  "  noomenon." 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  181 

Noumenon  should  not  mean  "  thing  in  itself,"  as 
which  it  is  actually  used  by  Kant  contrary  to  his  own 
definition,  but  man's  subjective  conception  of  the 
thing  in  itself.  If  the  phenomenon  is  subjective  ap 
pearance,  the  noumenon,  far  from  being  objective, 
is,  according  to  Kant,  still  more  subjective,  being  a 
mere  subjective  digest  of  the  materials  furnished  by 
the  subjective  phenomenon.  The  term  "noumenon," 
however,  is  not  limited  to  its  original  meaning.  Kant 
understands  by  it,  not  only  the  subjective  concept  of 
things,  but  also  the  objective  ''thing  in  itself." 

The  terms  a  priori  and  a  posteriori  are  of  special 
significance.  They  mean  "  before"  and  "afterwards," 
but  we  must  bear  in  mind  that  they  should  be  under 
stood,  not  as  a  temporal  succession,  but  in  a  logical 
sense.  A  priori  cognitions  are  the  principles  which 
the  naturalist  uses  in  his  investigations;  but  his  in 
vestigations  themselves,  consisting  of  sense-experi 
ence,  are  a  posteriori.  Before  he  begins  his  investiga 
tion,  the  naturalist  must  know  that  2X2=4,  that  there 
can  be  no  effect  without  a  cause,  that  he  can  rely  on 
the  rule  of  three  and  on  the  syllogisms  of  logic.  The 
knowledge  of  these  truths  is  the  condition  of  science, 
and  all  these  truths  are  universal,  i.  e.,  they  apply  to 
all  possible  cases.  A  priori  knowledge  has  developed 
through  the  practice  of  sense-experience.  Indeed, 
sense-experience  came  first  in  temporal  order ;  but 
sense-impressions  would  forever  remain  a  mass  of  iso 
lated  things  were  they  not  systematised  with  the  as 
sistance  of  a  priori  principles. 

A  priori  does  not  mean  innate,  for  neither  mathe"^"| 
matics,  nor  arithmetic,  nor  logic  is   innate;  but   the 
theorems  of  these   sciences  can  be   deduced   in   our 
thoughts  without  calling  upon  sense-experience  to  aid 


1 82  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

us.  Innate  ideas  would  mean  inherited  notions,  like 
the  instincts  of  animals.  The  characteristic  feature 
of  a  priori  conceptions  is  not  that  we  know  them  well 
nor  that  we  find  them  ready-made  in  our  minds,  but 
that  they  have  a  universal  application  and  are  there 
fore  necessary  truths. 

The  contrast  between  a  priori  and  a  posteriori 
truths  is  easily  explained  when  we  consider  that  the 
former  are  purely  formal,  the  latter  sensory.  The  for 
mer  therefore  cannot  give  us  any  information  concern 
ing  the  substance,  the  matter,  the  thingish  nature  of 
things  (as  Kant  expresses  it,  "they  are  empty"),  but 
they  can  be  used  for  determining  the  relations  and 
forms  of  things,  and  this  renders  them  uniquely  valu 
able,  for  science  is  nothing  but  a  tracing  of  the  changes 
of  form,  an  application  of  the  laws  of  form,  a  measur 
ing,  a  weighing,  a  counting  ;  and  their  paramount  im 
portance  appears  in  this  that  our  knowledge  of  the 
laws  of  form  will  in  consideration  of  their  universal 
validity,  result  in  the  possibility  of  predetermining 
future  modifications  under  given  conditions. 

There  are  two  synonyms  of  a  priori,  the  word 
"pure"  and  the  term  "transcendental." 

Reason  unalloyed  with  notions  derived  from  sense- 
experience,  and  therefore  limited  to  conceptions  a  pri 
ori,  is  called  pure  reason.  "Transcendental"  means 
practically  the  same  as  pure  and  a  priori.  By  tran 
scendental  discourses  Kant  understands  those  which 
transcend  experience  and  consider  its  a  priori  condi 
tions.  Thus,  transcendental  logic  is  pure  logic  in  so 
far  as  pure  logic  is  the  condition  of  applied  logic. 
Transcendental  psychology  is  the  doubtful  domain  of 
abstract  notions  concerning  the  unity  of  the  ego,  its 
substantiality  and  permanence,  etc.  Transcendental 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  183 

cosmology  consists  of  the  ideas  of  existence  in  gene 
ral  and  the  universe  in  particular.  Then  the  questions 
arise  as  to  the  world's  infinitude  or  limitedness,  its 
eternity  or  beginning  and  end.  Further,  whether  or 
not  causality  is  absolute,  viz.,  is  there  contingency 
only,  or  is  an  uncaused  will  possible?  Here  the  oracle 
of  pure  reason  fails  and  Kant  formulates  the  result  in 
his  strange  doctrine  of  contradictions,  or,  as  he  calls 
it,  antinomies  of  pure  reason. 

Transcendental  cosmology,  transcendental  psy 
chology,  transcendental  theology,  are  not  sciences, 
but  the  dreams  of  metaphysics.  As  such  they  tran 
scend  experience  to  the  extent  of  becoming  hazy. 
They  cease  to  be  accessible  to  comprehension  and  are 
then  in  Kant's  terminology  called  "  transcendent. " 

Mark  the  difference  between  the  two  terms :  the 
word  "transcendental"  denotes  the  subjective  condi 
tions  of  all  experience,  consisting  in  the  recognition 
of  such  truisms  as  logical,  arithmetical,  and  geometri 
cal  theorems,  which  are  the  clearest,  most  indisput 
able,  and  most  unequivocal  notions  we  have.  Tran 
scendent,  however,  means  that  which  lies  beyond  the 
ken  of  all  possible  knowledge  within  the  nebulous  do 
main  in  which  we  can  as  well  affirm  as  deny  the  pos 
sibility  of  assumptions.  Consider  at  the  same  time 
that  in  the  English  language  "transcendental"  is  a 
synonym  of  "transcendent,"  and  the  difference  made 
by  Kant  has  been  slurred  over  by  many  of  his  exposi 
tors.  What  a  heap  of  confusion  resulted  from  this 
carelessness  !  We  need  not  wonder  that  his  radical 
system  of  transcendental  criticism  was  transformed 
into  that  uncritical  metaphysicism,  or  dabbling  in  un 
warranted  transcendental  notions  which  Kant  so  vig 
orously  and  effectually  combated. 


184 

The  confusion  which  English  interpreters  produced 
by  their  neglect  of  distinguishing  between  "  transcen 
dent"  and  " transcendental"  was  increased  by  their 
misconception  of  the  term  Anschauung,  which,  being 
properly  but  not  adequately  translated  by  its  Latin 
equivalent  " intuition,"  became  tinged  with  all  the 
mysticism  and  metaphysicism  of  intuitionalism.  "In 
tuition,"  according  to  the  commonly  accepted  use  of 
the  word,  means  in  the  English  as  well  as  in  German 
"the  power  of  the  mind  by  which  it  immediately  per 
ceives  the  truth  of  things  without  reasoning  or  analy 
sis."  As  such  intuitions  signify  not  only  the  images 
of  sense-perception,  but  also,  and  indeed  mainly,  ec 
static  visions  in  which  the  soul  is  face  to  face  with 
presences  spiritual,  supernal,  or  divine ;  and  thus  it 
happened  that  under  the  guarantee  of  Kant's  criticism 
the  most  extravagant  speculations  could  gain  admis 
sion  to  the  philosophical  world  as  genuine  philosoph 
ical  ideas. 

Anschauung,  like  the  Latin  intuitio,  signifies  the 
act  of  looking  at  an  object ;  it  denotes  the  sensation  of 
sight.  However,  its  use  is  not  restricted  to  sight,  but 
extends  to  all  sense-perception.  The  peculiar  feature 
of  sense-perception  consists  in  its  directness  and  im 
mediate  appearance  in  our  organs  of  sense  as  sensa 
tion.  When  we  look  at  a  tree  we  do  not  argue ;  we 
simply  see  the  tree.  We  need  not  know  anything 
about  the  physical  processes  that  take  place  both 
outside  in  the  domain  of  ether-waves  which  are  re 
flected  on  the  sighted  object,  and  within  our  eye 
where  the  lens  produces  an  image  that  is  thrown  upon 
the  surface  of  the  retina,  in  the  same  way  in  which 
the  photographer's  camera  produces  a  picture  on  the 
sensitive  plate.  The  picture  seen  is  the  result  of  the 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  185 

process,  and  all  epistemological  considerations  are 
after-thoughts.  The  same  is  true  of  all  sensations. 
Sensations,  though  the  result  of  complicated  pro 
cesses,  are  given  facts;  they  are  the  data  of  experi 
ence  and  there  is  no  argument  in  them,  no  reasoning, 
no  deliberation,  no  hesitation,  as  to  their  truth;  they 
are  the  realities  of  life,  and  from  them  we  construct 
our  notions  of  the  world  in  which  we  live. 

It  is  a  pity  that  we  have  not  a  Saxon  equivalent 
for  the  German  Anschauung.  We  might  coin  the  word 
11  atsight,"  which  (in  contrast  to  insight)  would  de 
note  the  act  of  perceiving  a  sighted  object  ;  but  the 
word,  in  order  to  make  the  same  impression,  ought 
to  be  current,  which  the  term  atsight  is  not.  The 
translation  ''intuition"  is  admissible  only  on  the  con 
dition  that  we  exclude  from  it  all  mystical  notions  of 
subjective  visions  and  define  it  as  visualised  percep 
tion.  There  are  passages  where  Anschauung  is  an  ex 
act  synonym  for  "sense-experience"  or  "perception," 
and  we  might  translate  it  thus  were  it  not  for  the  ex 
tended  use  Kant  makes  of  the  term  by  speaking  of 
reinc  Anschauung,  meaning  thereby  the  pure  forms  of 
sense-experience  which  are  as  much  immediate  data 
of  perception  as  are  the  sense-elements  of  sensation. 

If  we  had  to  recast  the  exposition  of  Kant's  phi 
losophy  we  could  avoid  the  term  "pure  intuition" 
and  replace  it  by  the  pure  forms  of  sense-experience, 
but  if  we  would  render  Kant  in  his  own  words  we  can 
not  do  so.  The  translator  must  reproduce  Kant  in 
his  own  language,  and  thus  must  either  invent  a  new 
word  such  as  atsight,  or  must  cling  to  the  traditional 
term  intuition.^ 

1  Mr.  Kroeger'c  proposition,  made  in  tha  Journal  a/  Speculation  Philo*- 
epky,  II.,  p.  191,  to  translate  Anschauung  by  contemplation  »eaoia  inadmis- 


186  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 


KANT'S  IDEALISM. 

The  contrasts  in  Kant's  terminology,  a  priori  and 
a  posteriori,  formal  and  material,  pure  reason  and  ex 
perience,  etc.,  do  not  yet  imply  the  conclusion  at 
which  he  arrives,  the  main  result  being  the  ideality  of 
space  and  time  and  of  all  pure  forms  of  thought. 
Kant  was  led  to  it  by  a  strange  fallacy,  the  error  of 
which  we  intend  to  trace  in  the  subsequent  pages. 

First  let  us  try  to  understand  the  point  of  view 
which  Kant  took. 

The  pure  form  of  our  sense-perception  is  the  rela 
tional  in  the  domain  of  sensory  elements,  viz.,  their 
juxtaposition,  or  space,  and  their  succession,  or  time, 
their  shape,  their  causal  intercatenation,  etc. 

In  his  discourse  on  the  pure  forms  of  sense-per 
ception  (called  "Transcendental  ^Esthetics"),  Kant 
points  out  first  of  space,  then  of  time,  that  they  are 
notions  which  are  : 

1.  Insuppressible  (viz.,  we  can  think  or  assume  in 
thought  the  non-existence  of  all  objects,  but  not  cf 
space  or  time). 

2.  Necessary  a  priori  (viz.,  they  are  of  universal 
application  and  transcendental,  i.  e.,  the  condition  of 
all  sense-perceptions.) 

3.  Unique  (viz.,  there  is  but  one  space  and  one 
time;  all  spaces,  so  called,  are  parts  only  of,  or  rooni 
in,  that  one  space;  and  different  times  are  periods  o 
that  one  time). 

4.  Infinite    (viz.,    all   concrete   objects   are  finite; 

sible.  Compare  for  further  details  of  the  use  of  the  word  the  author's  pam 
phlet  Kant  and  Spencer,  pp.  76  ff.  In  the  present  translation  of  Kant's 
Prolegomena  we  have  rendered  it  a  few  times  by  sense-perception  and  -visuali 
sation,  but  mostly  by  intuition,  and  have  (wherever  it  is  not  translated  by 
"intuition")  alway  added  ii;  parenthesis  the  German  original. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  187 

but  time  and  space,  not  being  concrete  entities,  are 
limitless). 

He  concludes  that  space  and  time  are  not  proper 
ties  of  objects  as  things-in-themselves,  but  the  forms 
of  their  phenomenal  existence. 

It  is  obviously  a  mistake  to  regard  space  and  time 
as  concrete  objects.  Infinite  objects  would  be  mon 
ster-existences  the  reality  of  which  cannot  but  pass 
our  comprehension.  They  are  the  forms  of  thing?, 
indispensable  not  only  for  their  existence  in  general 
but  also  for  determining  their  several  individual  and 
characteristic  types ;  for  that  which  constitutes  the 
difference  of  things,  so  far  as  science  has  been  able  to 
penetrate  into  the  mysteries  of  being,  is  always  due 
to  a  difference  of  form.  Kant  guardedly  grants  em 
pirical  reality  to  space  and  time;  he  ascribes  space 
and  time  to  things  as  phenomena,  and  denies  only 
their  being  properties  of  things  as  things-in-them 
selves.  But  he  adds  the  explicit  statement  that  space 
as  well  as  time  are.  "the  subjective  conditions  of  the 
sensibility  under  which  alone  external  intuition  (An- 
schauung,  \.  e.,  sense-perception)  becomes  possible." 
Thus,  Kant  concludes  space  and  time  are  a  priori  in 
tuitions;  they  do  not  belong  to  the  external  domain 
of  reality  or  objectivity,  but  to  the  sphere  of  subjec 
tivity;  and  being  forms  of  the  sensibility  of  the  in 
tuitive  mind  they  are  (says  Kant)  ideal. 

Kant  does  not  deny  the  reality  of  things,  but  hav 
ing  established  the  ideality  of  space  and  time  he  be 
lieves  that, 

"If  we  regarded  space  and  time  as  properties  which  must  le 
found  in  objects  as  things-in-themselves,  as  sine  quibus  von  c  f 
the  possibility  of  their  existence,  and  reflect  on  the  absurdities  in 
which  \ve  then  find  our  ^Ives  involved,  inasmuch  as  we  are  com- 


1 88  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

pelled  to  admit  the  existence  of  two  infinite  things,  which  are 
nevertheless  not  substances,  nor  anything  really  inhering  in  sub 
stances,  nay,  to  admit  that  they  are  the  necessary  conditions  of  the 
existence  of  all  things,  and  moreover,  that  they  must  continue  to 
exist,  although  all  existing  things  were  annihilated, — we  cannot 
blame  the  good  Berkeley  for  degrading  bodies  to  mere  illusory  ap 
pearances.  Nay,  even  or.r  own  existence  which  would  in  this  case 
depend  upon  the  self-existent  reality  of  such  a  mere  nonentity  as 
time,  would  necessarily  be  changed  with  it  into  mere  appearance — 
an  absurdity  which  no  one  has  as  yet  been  guilty  of."1 

Thus,  Kant  believes  that  if  space  and  time  were 
objective  they  would  impart  their  ideality  to  the  ob 
jective  world  and  change  it  to  mere  appearance;  by 
conceiving  space  and  time  (and  in  addition  to  the 
forms  of  our  sensibility  also  the  forms  of  our  think 
ing)  as  purely  ideal,  viz.,  as  subjective  properties  of 
the  mind,  he  assures  us  that  the  world,  our  own  ex 
istence  included,  will  be  saved  from  the  general  col 
lapse  which  it  otherwise  in  his  opinion  must  suffer. 

KANT  AND  SWEDENBORG. 

The  development  of  Kant's  theory  of  the  ideality 
of  space  and  time  coincides  with  his  investigation  of 
Swedenborg's  philosophy,  if  that  word  be  applicable 
to  a  world-conception  which  afterwards  was  denom 
inated  by  Kant  himself  as  "dreams  of  a  visionary." 
Swedenborgians  claim  that  Kant  was  influenced  by 
Swedenborg  in  the  formulation  of  his  critical  ideal 
ism  ;  and  Mr.  Albert  J.  Edmunds  discusses  the  sub 
ject  in  an  article  which  appeared  in  the  New  Church 
Review,  Vol.  IV.,  No.  2,  under  the  title:  Time  and 
Space:  Hints  Given  by  Swedenborg  to  KanL  While  it 
appears  that  there  is  less  borrowing  on  the  part  of 
Kant  than  can  be  made  out  by  Swedenborg's  adher- 

1  Critique  of  Pure  Reason,  Supplement  VI.  of  2nd  edition. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  189 

ents,  there  is  more  justice  in  the  claim  of  Sweden- 
borg's  influence  over  Kant  than  seems  to  be  palatable 
to  such  Kant  scholars  as  is  Professor  Vaihinger. 
Frank  Sewall,  the  editor  of  the  New  Church  Review, 
goes  over  the  field  in  an  article  entitled  :  Kant  ana 
Swedenborg  on  Cognition,  in  which  he  makes  out  a 
good  case  scarcely  less  favorable  for  Swedenborg  than 
does  Edmunds.  The  fact  is  that  the  mystical  ideas 
on  space  and  time  which  permeate  religious  thought 
had  their  effect  on  Swedenborg  as  much  as  on  other 
thinkers,  mystics  as  well  as  philosophers,  and  among 
the  latter,  on  Kant ;  and  certain  formulations  of  the 
problem  which  can  be  found  in  Swedenborg,  did  not 
strike  Kant  as  much  as  may  appear  by  a  mere  com 
parison  of  the  passages. 

Mr.  Edmunds  quotes  the  following  passages  from 
Leibnitz,  on  space  and  time  : 

"Since  space  in  itself  is  an  ideal  thing  like  time,  it  must  nec 
essarily  follow  that  space  outside  the  world  is  imaginary,  as  even 
the  schoolmen  have  acknowledged  it  to  be.  The  same  is  the  case 
with  empty  space  in  the  world — which  I  still  believe  to  be  imagin 
ary,  for  the  reasons  which  I  have  set  forth."  (V.  33.) 

"  There  is  no  space  at  all  where  there  is  no  matter."     (V.  62.) 

"Space  .  .  .  is  something  ideal."     (V.  104.) 

"  The  immensity  of  God  is  independent  of  space,  as  the  eter 
nity  of  God  is  independent  of  time."  (V.  106.) 

"Had  there  been  no  creatures,  space  and  time  would  only 
have  existed  in  the  ideas  of  God."  (Paper  IV.  41.) 

Here  Leibnitz  uses  the  very  word  "ideal,"  of  both 
space  and  time.  Incidentally  we  must  add  that  natu 
ralists  of  to-day  will  no  longer  countenance  Leibnitz's 
view  of  the  non-existence  of  empty  space. 

There  is  even  the  religious  mysticism  displayed  by 
Leibnitz  which  makes  God  independent  of  space  and 
time.  Swedenborg  says  the  same  about  the  angels : 


190  KAMI'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

"The  angels  have  no  idea  of  time.  Such  is  the  case  in  the 
world  of  spirits  and  still  more  perfectly  in  heaven :  how  much 
more  before  the  Lord."  (Arcana  Ccelestia,  1274.) 

It  is  a  fact  that  Kant  had  read  Swedenborg,  but 
the  coincidences  as  to  the  ideality  of  space  and  time 
and  the  theory  of  cognition  are  trivial  as  compared 
with  the  coincidences  with  former  philosophers,  such 
as  Leibnitz.  The  truth  is,  we  have  in  Swedenborg 
the  type  of  a  religious  thinker  who  formulates  his 
conception  of  space  and  time  and  other  metaphysical 
doctrines  in  the  shape  of  mystical  allegories,  after  the 
fashion  of  Jacob  Boehme  and  other  religious  vision 
aries.  It  is  wrong  on  the  one  side  to  overestimate  his 
mystical  expressions,  which  are  commonplace  among 
authors  of  his  ilk,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  to  ridicule 
them  as  purely  visionary,  devoid  of  philosophical 
value.  It  is  characteristic  of  the  human  mind  at  a 
certain  stage  of  its  development  to  formulate  in  mys 
tical  language  philosophical  conceptions  which  lie 
beyond  the  grasp  of  the  intellect  of  that  peculiar  stage 
of  growth.  It  is  the  religious  attitude  of  approaching 
philosophical  problems  in  niyst:cal  expressions.  While 
it  is  natural  for  a  scientist  to  ridicule  the  mystic  for 
claiming  to  have  solved  the  world-problem  though 
producing  nothing  but  air-bubbles,  it  is  at  the  same 
time  a  one-sidedness  to  see  in  mysticism  nothing  but 
wild  and  worthless  hallucinations.  Mysticism  is  a 
solution  of  the  world-problem  by  sentiment,  and  it 
affords  the  great  advantage  of  determining  and  estab 
lishing  the  moral  attitude  of  its  devotees.  Considered 
as  science  it  is  absolutely  worthless,  considered  as  a 
guide  in  life  its  worth  is  determined  by  the  spirit  of 
which  it  is  born.  Where  the  religious  sentiment  i; 
serious,  deep,  and  noble,  mysticism  will  find  a  poeti- 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  191 

cal  expression  full  of  significance,  depth,  and  aspira 
tion.  Kant  as  a  religious  man  was  attracted  by  Swe- 
denborg,  but  when  he  weighed  his  revelations  as  phi 
losophy  he  was  so  disappointed  that  he  felt  ashamed 
of  having  been  caught  among  the  credulous  investi 
gators  of  occult  phenomena. 

Swedenborg  is  one  of  the  most  representative  mys 
tics,  and  while  his  books  may  be  worthless  as  philo 
sophical  treatises,  they  are  not  only  interesting  to  the 
scientist  because  typical  of  a  certain  phase  in  the  reli 
gious  development  of  human  nature,  but  also  classi 
cal  as  mystical  literature.  The  appreciation  which  he 
has  found  among  a  number  of  adherents  proves  too 
well  how  deeply  his  way  of  presenting  metaphysical 
problems  in  the  shape  of  allegorical  dreams  is  founded 
in  the  peculiar  constitution  of  man's  spiritual  system. 
Those  who  took  the  trouble  to  investigate  his  miracles 
and  prophecies  found  that,  however  much  might  be 
surmised,  nothing  could  be  definitely  proved,  except 
the  fact  that  there  are  people  of  fair  and  sometimes 
even  extraordinary  intelligence  who  have  a  decided 
inclination  to  believe  in  occult  phenomena,  that  they, 
though  subjectively  honest,  can  easily  become  con 
vinced  of  things  which  they  are  anxious  to  believe, 
and  finally  that  in  minds  where  a  vivid  imagination 
checks  the  development  of  critical  acumen,  the  poeti 
cal  conceptions  of  religious  faith  grow  so  definite  and 
concrete  as  to  become  indistinguishable  from  actual 
life  and  reality. 

Now,  what  are  the  lessons  of  the  relation  of  mysti 
cism  to  science? 

We  ought  to  consider  that  certain  metaphysical 
truths  (as  to  the  nature  of  space,  time,  our  mode  of 
cognition,  causation,  infinity,  eternity,  etc.),  when 


192  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

stated  in  abstract  formulas,  seem  dry  and  unmeaning 
to  unscientific  minds,  yet  they  possess  a  deep  religious 
significance  which  finds  allegorical  expression  in  the 
various  religious  systems  in  myths,  ceremonial  insti 
tutions,  and  dogmas.  By  sensual  natures  who  cling 
to  the  allegorical  feature  of  the  allegory,  they  can  be 
appreciated  only  if  they  are  expressed  in  a  sensual 
way,  if  spiritual  truths  are  told  in  parables  of  concrete 
instances  as  if  they  were  material  facts  of  the  material 
world.  It  is  characteristic  of  mystical  minds  to  live 
in  an  atmosphere  of  sensual  symbolism  in  such  a  way 
that  they  believe  their  own  dreams,  and  their  assur 
ance  makes  their  statement  so  convincing  that  they 
easily  find  followers  among  those  who  are  kin  to  them 
in  their  mental  constitution.  As  soon  as  a  critical 
reader  tries  to  verify  the  statements  of  such  men,  he 
finds  himself  irritated  by  a  heap  of  worthless  evidence, 
and  the  result  is  an  indignation  such  as  Kant  showed 
after  his  perusal  of  Swedenborg's  Arcana. 

The  following  summarised  statement  of  Sweden 
borg's  world-conception  is  given  by  Kant  in  his  Essay 
on  Swcdenborg,  which  appeared  in  1766  :l 

"  Each  human  soul  has  in  this  life  its  place  in  the  spirit-world, 
and  belongs  to  a  certain  society,  -which  in  every  case  is  in  harmony 
with  its  internal  condition  of  truth  and  good,  that  is,  of  under 
standing  and  will.  But  the  location  of  spirits  among  themselves 
has  nothing  in  common  with  space  in  the  material  world.  The 
soul  of  one  man,  therefore,  in  India  can  be  next-door  neighbor  to 
that  of  another  in  Europe,  so  far  as  spiritual  position  is  con 
cerned;  while  those  who,  as  to  the  body,  live  in  one  house,  may 
I  e  quite  far  enough  distant  from  one  another  as  to  those  [that  is, 
spiritual]  conditions.  When  man  dies  his  soul  does  not  change  its 
place,  but  only  perceives  itself  in  the  same  wherein,  with  regard 
to  other  spirits,  it  already  was  in  this  life.  Besides,  although  the 

1  We  quote  from  Mr.  Albert  J  Edmunds's  essay  in  the  New  Church  Review, 
Vol.  IV.,  p.  a6i. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  193 

mutual  relation  of  spirits  is  not  in  real  space,  yet  it  has  to  them  the 
appearance  of  space,  and  their  relations  are  represented,  with  their 
accompanying  conditions,  as  nearnesses;  their  differences  as  dis 
tances,  even  as  the  spirits  themselves  have  not  really  extension, 
yet  present  to  one  another  the  appearance  of  a  human  form.  In 
this  imaginary  space  there  is  a  plenary  community  of  spiritual 
natures.  Swedenborg  speaks  with  departed  souls  whenever  he 
pleases,  etc." 

Now,  if  we  comprehend  that  besides  the  causal 
connexion  of  things  in  space  and  time  there  is  a  logical 
interrelation  which  appertains  to  pure  reason,  we  shall 
come  to  the  conclusion  that  Swedenborg's  ideas  are 
quite  legitimate,  if  they  are  but  understood  to  be  poet 
ical  and  if  we  are  permitted  to  conceive  them  in  a 
strictly  scientific  sense.  We  read  : 

"  The  soul  of  one  man  in  India  can  be  next-door  neighbor  to 
that  of  another  in  Europe  so  far  as  spiritual  position  is  concerned; 
while  those  who  as  to  the  body  live  in  one  house  may  be  quite  far 
enough  distant  from  one  another  as  to  those  (that  is,  spiritual) 
conditions." 

Now,  it  is  obvious  that  this  sympathy  of  souls, 
which  is  not  according  to  space  and  time,  but  accord 
ing  to  spiritual  kinship,  is  quite  legitimate  and  very 
important  to  those  who  understand  it.  The  sensual 
man  will  find  difficulty  in  grasping  its  significance,  ex 
cept  that  it  be  stated  to  him  in  a  sensual  way.  Ob 
viously,  it  is  true  that  "spirits  themselves  have  not 
really  extension."  Their  interrelation  is  of  a  different 
kind.  But  if  we  imagine  them,  as  Swedenborg  does, 
"to  present  to  one  another  the  appearance  of  a  hu 
man  form,"  we  conceive  of  their  existence  as  though 
it  were  in  space,  another  kind  of  space  than  that  filled 
by  matter,  and  "in  this  imaginary  space  there  is  a 
plenary  community  of  spiritual  natures."  Thus  logi 
cians  represent  the  interrelation  between  genus  and 


194  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

species  by  geometrical  figure,  the  one  including  the 
oilier. 

Swedenborg  is  simply  a  man  whose  imagination  is 
so  vivid  and  whose  scientific  criticism  is  so  little  de 
veloped  that  the  imaginary  space  invented  to  repre 
sent  the  interrelations  of  spiritual  realities  which  are 
in  neither  space  nor  time,  becomes  an  actual  space 
to  him  ;  his  spirits  become  materialised  shapes,  and 
thus  it  happens  that  he  can  speak  "with  departed 
souls  whenever  he  pleases."  A  scientist  too,  a  his 
torian  or  a  naturalist,  can  consult  the  wisdom  of  the 
departed  spirits.  He  can  make  himself  acquainted 
with  the  views  of  Newton,  of  Goethe,  of  Kant;  he 
can  incorporate  their  souls  in  his  own  being,  but  being 
of  a  critical  nature,  he  will  not  see  them  as  bodily 
shapes.  It  is  characteristic  of  mystics  that  their  im 
agination  outruns  their  sobriety,  and  thus  the  flights 
of  their  fancy  become  real  to  them. 

While  it  is  not  impossible  that  Swedenborg  be 
came  the  fulcrum  on  which  Kant  elaborated  his  meta 
physics,  we  may  at  the  same  time  justify  the  oppo 
site  statement  that  Kant's  relation  to  Swedenborg  is 
purely  incidental  and  without  significance.  The  elab 
oration  of  his  theories  as  to  space  and  time  and  cogni 
tion,  Kant  made  at  the  time  when  he  read  Sweden- 
borg's  works,  but  we  must  be  aware  of  the  fact  that 
Kant  was  familiar  with  mystic  views  in  general,  and 
Swedenborg's  expressions  did  not  strike  him  as  much 
as  it  might  appear  to  those  who  compare  Swedenborg 
and  Kant  only,  but  have  no  reference  to  Leibnitz  and 
other  thinkers.  Certainly,  Kant  would  have  come  to 
the  same  conclusion  if  he  had  dealt  with  any  other 
thinker  of  a  similar  type,  Jacob  Boehme,  or  even 
spirits  on  a  lower  level  in  the  line  of  mysticism. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  195 

While  Kant's  statements  show  a  certain  resem 
blance  to  those  of  S\vedenborg,  we  find  that  their 
agreement  with  Leibnitz  (a  philosopher  whom  both 
Immanuels,  the  great  mystic  as  well  as  the  great 
critic,  had  studied  carefully)  is  much  closer.  We  shall 
at  the  same  time  understand  why  Kant  exhibited  a  de 
cided  contempt  and  scorn  for  the  dreamy  haziness  of 
these  visionaries,  which,  when  dealing  with  scientific 
problems,  is  sterile  and  unprofitable.  In  contrasting 
the  philosophical  study  of  metaphysics  with  those 
vague  fancies  of  religio-philosophical  dreams,  Kant 
compared  the  latter  to  the  intangible  shade  of  a  de 
parted  spirit,  quoting  Virgil's  well-known  verses  where 
Mneas  in  the  under-world  tries  to  embrace  the  soul  of 
his  departed  father,  Anchises.1  Kant  says: 

"  Metaphysics,  with  whom  it  is  my  destiny  to  be  in  love,  offers 
two  advantages,  although  I  have  but  seldom  been  favored  by  her: 
the  first  is,  to  solve  the  problems  which  the  investigating  mind 
raises  when  it  is  on  the  track  of  the  more  hidden  properties  of 
things  through  reason.     But  here  the  result  very  frequently  de 
ceives  hope,  and  has  also  in  this  case  escaped  our  longing  hands. 
"Ter  frustra  comprensa  manus  effugit  imago, 
Par  levibus  ventis  volucrique  simillima  somno." — (VIRGIL.) 
[Thrice  I  tried  to  embrace  and  thrice  it  escaped  me,  the  image, 
Airy  and  light  as  the  wind,  and  to  volatile  dreams  to  be  likened.] 

KANT'S  ANTINOMIES. 

After  this  digression  we  revert  to  Kant's  idealism 
And  will  now  point  out  the  result  to  which  it  leads. 

Kant,  as  we  have  seen,  protests  against  being  an 
idealist  in  the  sense  that  the  reality  of  the  external 
world  of  objects  or  things  be  denied.  His  idealism 
insists  only  on  the  ideality  of  space  and  time ;  and  by 
ideality  he  understands  subjectivity.  But  together 

,  Book  VI.,  Verses  701-702. 


196  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

with  time  and  space  all  our  forms  of  thought  are  as 
sumed  to  be  purely  ideal.  Hence  there  is  a  rift  rend 
ing  asunder  form  and  substance,  thought  and  reality, 
representative  image  or  phenomenon  and  the  repre 
sented  objects.  We  know  phenomena,  not  noumena. 
Things  in  themselves  are  unknowable,  for  the  laws  of 
pure  form  have  reference  to  appearances  only. 

If  purely  formal  thought  has  no  objective  value,  it 
can  be  used  merely  to  decide  problems  that  lie  within 
the  range  of  experience — the  domain  of  appearance; 
but  things  in  themselves,  the  domain  of  transcendent 
existence,  lies  without  the  pale  of  any  possible  knowl 
edge. 

Kant's  method  of  dealing  with  these  subjects  is 
peculiar.  He  neither  leaves  them  alone  nor  solves 
them,  but  formulates  the  affirmations  as  well  as  the 
negations  of  a  series  of  contradictory  statements  in 
what  he  calls  "the  antinomies."  Here  the  weakness 
of  Kant's  philosophy  comes  out,  indicating  that  there 
must  be  a  flaw  in  it  somewhere. 

It  is  interesting  to  notice  that  as  to  Kant's  Antino 
mies  of  Pure  Reason  the  great  Konigsberg  philosopher 
has  been  anticipated  by  Buddhism  in  which  (accord 
ing  to  Neumann's  Reden  Gautama's,  Vol.  II.,  Nos.  60 
and  72)  the  antinomies  are  taught  in  a  similar,  partly 
literally  in  the  same,  form.  But  there,  too,  the  con 
tradiction  belongs  to  the  formulation  of  the  statement 
of  facts,  not  to  the  facts  themselves. 

In  a  certain  sense  we  can  say,  the  world  must  have 
had  a  beginning,  and  must  come  to  an  end ;  and  the 
world  had  no  beginning  and  can  have  no  end.  If  we 
speak  of  this  definite  nebular  system  of  stars  compris 
ing  the  entire  milky  way  we  are  compelled  to  admit 
that  it  began  and  will  at  some  definite  though  distant 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  197 

future  be  dissolved  again  ;  but  if  we  mean  by  world 
the  totality  of  existence  in  all  its  shapes,  prior  forms 
and  causes  of  origin,  we  must  own  that  it  has  existed 
and  ever  will  exist.  We  could  go  back  in  thought  to 
the  time  before  the  present  cosmos  started,  when 
other  worlds  were  evolving  or  dissolving  and  a  differ 
ent  kind  of  universe  or  condition  of  things  prevailed 
and  so  on  without  coming  to  an  end.  But  these  con 
ditions  being  the  causes  of  the  present  world  are  in 
cluded  in  our  concept  of  the  universe.  The  antino 
mies  are  due  to  the  equivocal  significance  of  our 
words,  not  to  a  fault  of  reason ;  nor  do  they  indicate 
that  existence  itself  is  self-contradictory.  The  con 
tradiction  is  not  in  the  things  but  in  our  conception 
of  things.1 

Schopenhauer  has  vigorously  attacked  Kant  on 
account  of  his  antinomies,  insinuating  weakness  and 
hypocrisy.  But  it  seems  to  us,  while  by  no  means 
agreeing  with  Kant  on  this  particular  point,  that 
granting  his  premises  his  conclusion  was  justified. 
The  four  points  of  the  antinomies,  viz.,  the  eternity 
and  infinite  divisibility  of  the  world,  the  contrast  of 
freedom  to  causation  and  the  existence  of  God,  are 
no  longer  of  a  purely  formal  nature;  some  notions  of 
experience  are  inevitably  mixed  up  in  them,  and  thus 

iThat  the  antinomies  cannot  be  regarded  as  true  antinomies  or  contra 
dictions  of  reason,  but  as  the  result  of  a  misconception  and  lack  of  clearness 
in  our  formulation  of  the  several  problems,  becomes  apparent  in  the  antin 
omy  of  freedom  -versus  necessity.  Karl's  definition  of  freedom  (§  53)  as  a  fac 
ulty  of  starting  a  chain  of  events  spontaneously  without  antecedent  causes 
and  his  way  of  reconciling  freedom  and  nature  (or  as  we  would  say  "  deter 
minism")  is  subject  to  serious  criticism.  Compare  the  author's  solution  of 
the  problem  in  Fundamental  Problems,  pp.  191-196;  Ethical  Problems,  pp.  45- 
50,  152-156;  Primer  of  Philosophy,  pp.  159-164;  Soul  of  Man,  pp.  389-397.  See 
also  The  Monist,  Vol.  III.,  pp.  611  ff.,  "The  Future  in  Mental  Causation." 
Concerning  the  ought  and  its  assumed  mysterious  nature  compare  the  chap 
ters  "The  Is  and  the  Ought  "  and  "An  Analysis  of  the  Moral  Ought,"  in  The 
Ethical  Problem,  pp.  279-295. 


igS 

pure  reason  is  unable  to  decide  either  way.  We  might 
as  well  try  to  determine  by  a  pru,ri  considerations  as 
to  whether  or  not  electricity  can  be  produced  by  fric 
tion,  or  whether  or  not  by  rubbing  an  old  metal  lamp 
the  genii  of  the  lamp  will  appear.  Hence,  before  the 
tribunal  of  pure  reason  either  side,  the  affirmative  as 
well  as  the  negative,  is  defensible,  and  thus  we  should 
be  obliged  to  settle  the  question  with  other  methods ; 
other  methods,  however,  according  to  Kant's  notions 
concerning  the  nature  of  metaphysical  questions, 
would  not  be  admissible,  because  he  insists  that  all 
metaphysical  notions  must  be  derived  from  pure  con 
cepts  alone. 

KANT'S  PROBLEM. 

Kant's  philosophy  has  become  the  beginning  of  a 
:  *w  epoch  in  the  evolution  of  human  thought  through 
a  formulation  of  its  basic  problem  and  by  starting  out 
in  the  right  direction  for  its  solution ;  but  Kant  has 
not  spoken  the  final  word. 

Kant  was  awakened  from  his  dogmatic  slumber  by 
Hume's  scepticism,  and  it  was  Hume's  problem  as  to 
the  nature  of  causation  which  prompted  him  to  strike 
a  new  path  in  the  conception  of  philosophical  prob 
lems. 

Kant  threw  light  on  Hume's  problem  by  general 
ising  it  and  recognising  the  kinship  of  the  concep 
tion  of  causation  to  mathematics  and  logic,  all  of  them 
beiiig  purely  formal  knowledge.  The  significance  of 
forrm  I  thought  and  its  power  of  affording  a  priori  cog- 
nitioi  •,  is  Kant's  peculiar  problem. 

It  s  generally  conceded  that  Kant  solved  Hume's 
probl  n,  but  he  failed  to  solve  his  own. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  199 

By  a  strange  misapprehension  of  the  nature  of  form 
and  its  non-objectivity,  he  has  switched  off  into  an 
idealism  (so  called  by  himself)  which  it  will  be  hard 
to  distinguish  from  that  subjectivism  which  he  as 
sumed  Berkeley's  philosophy  to  be.  The  difference 
between  the  two  (in  Kant's  opinion)  consists  in  this, 
that  according  to  Kant,  the  world  itself  is  real  but  in 
the  form  in  which  it  represents  itself  in  space  and 
time  it  is  phenomenal,  while  he  declares  that  accord 
ing  to  Berkeley  the  world  itself  is  "illusory  appear 
ance."  Further  Kant  insists  that  the  world  as  appear 
ance,  though  purely  phenomenal,  is  not  an  arbitrary 
illusion,  but  governed  by  laws  which  render  it  neces 
sary  in  all  its  details. 

The  great  merit  of  Kant  is  his  wonderfully  keen 
discrimination  between  the  purely  formal  and  the  sen 
sory,  showing  that  the  former  is  throughout  universal 
and  necessary  in  its  principles,  while  the  latter  is  in 
cidental  and  concrete  or  particular;  but  he  fails  to 
apply  the  same  discrimination  to  his  conception  of 
experience  and  to  the  objects  of  experience,  and  thus 
he  limits  the  formal  to  the  subject,  while  it  is  obvi 
ously  the  universal  feature  of  all  existence,  objective 
as  well  as  subjective,  constituting  between  them  the 
connecting  link  that  makes  science,  i.  e.,  objective 
cognition,  possible. 

Before  we  examine  Kant's  position,  we  must  first 
discuss,  at  least  briefly,  Hume's  problem  and  offer  the 
solution  in  the  form  which  Kant,  in  our  opinion,  ought 
to  have  given  it.  It  will  then  be  easy  to  point  out  the 
error  that  led  him  astray  and  prevented  him  from 
offering  a  definite  and  final  doctrine  as  to  the  nature 
of  form  which  should  become  the  basis  of  all  scientific 
inquiry,  and  enable  philosophy  to  become  a  science  a? 


200  KANT  S  PHILOSOPHY. 

definite,  or  nearly  so,  as  are  mathematics  and   logic, 
or  even  physics. 

HUME'S  PROBLEM. 

Locke  objected  to  the  doctrine  of  innate  ideas, 
claiming  that  all  ideas  were  the  products  of  sense- 
impressions,  and  he  excepted  only  one  idea,  viz.,  the 
principle  of  necessary  connexion,  i.  e.,  causality. 
Hume  accepted  Locke's  sensualism,  but,  endeavoring 
to  be  more  consistent,  drew  its  last  consequence  by 
denying  even  the  idea  of  cause  and  effect  as  a  neces 
sary  connexion.  He  argued  that  we  meet  with  con 
stant  conjunctions  in  experience,  but  not  with  neces 
sity.  By  habit  we  are  compelled  to  expect  that  upon 
every  cause  its  due  effect  will  follow,  but  there  is  no 
reason  to  assume  that  causation  is  due  to  a  universal 
and  necessary  law  of  objective  validity.  Hume  saw 
in  the  relation  between  cause  and  effect  a  synthesis, 
calling  it  "the  sequence  of  two  objects";  and  if  it 
were  a  synthesis,  or  a  mere  sequence,  he  would  be 
right  that  the  connexion  between  cause  and  effect  is 
accidental  and  our  belief  in  its  necessity  a  mere  habit. 

The  truth  is  that  causation  is  not  a  sequence  of 
two  objects  following  one  another,  but  one  process,  a 
motion,  or  a  change  of  place ;  and  the  simplest  kind 
of  motion  implies  that  there  are  at  least  three  phases 
or  states  of  things  in  the  system  in  which  the  motion 
takes  place  :  first  the  original  condition  (which  for  sim 
plicity's  sake  we  may  assume  to  be  in  a  relative  equi 
librium);  secondly,  the  motion  disturbing  the  equi 
librium  so  as  to  make  one  or  several  elements  in  the 
system  seek  new  places;  and  thirdly,  the  new  adjust 
ment  (which  for  simplicity's  sake  we  will  again  regard 
as  being  in  equilibrium).  The  first  phase  is  called 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY,  201 

the  conditions  or  circumstances,  the  second  is  the 
cause,  and  the  third  the  effect.  Cause  and  effect  are 
not  combined  into  a  unity  by  the  compulsion  of  a  law 
of  necessary  connexion ;  they  are  two  phases  of  one 
and  the  same  process.  The  duality  is  a  product  of 
abstraction  ;  the  unity  of  the  two  is  the  original  fact, 
and  we  know  now  that  causality  is  but  another  ex 
pression  for  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  matter  and 
energy.  The  naturalist  assumes  that  matter  and  en 
ergy  are  indestructible,  and  thus  every  process  that 
takes  place  in  nature  is  only  a  transformation.  Ac 
cordingly,  our  belief  in  causation  is  after  all,  although 
Hume  denied  it,  finally  based  upon  the  logical  prin 
ciple  of  identity  A=A.  It  is  an  extension  of  this  prin 
ciple  to  a  state  of  motion. 

,  Cause,  accordingly,  is  never  an  object,  but  always 
an  event,  viz.,  a  motion  of  some  kind.  We  cannot 
call  the  bullet  the  cause  and  death  the  effect ;  or  mer 
cury  the  cause  and  paralysis  the  effect;  or  worse  still 
(as  says  George  Lewes)  that  whiskey,  water,  sugar, 
and  lemon  are  the  causes  of  punch. 

We  distinguish  between  cause  and  reason,  reason 
being  the  law  under  which  a  single  event  is  subsumed 
for  the  sake  of  explaining  the  effectiveness  of  the 
cause.1 

IThe  instinct  of  language  has  here  proved  wiser  than  the  scholarship  of 
philosophers.  All  European  languages  (the  Greek,  the  Latin,  together  with 
its  derivatives  the  French,  Italian,  etc.,  the  German,  the  English)  distin 
guish  between  "  ain'a,  causa,  Ursache  (from  the  same  root  as  the  English  verb 
'to  seek')  cause,"  and  "apx*?  (i.  e.,  first  principle)  ratio,  Grund,  reason," 
the  former  being  the  particular  incident  that  starts  a  process,  the  latter  the 
raison  d'ftre,  the  principle,  or  general  rule,  the  natural  law  that  explains  it. 
When  the  two  ideas  are  confounded  as  has  been  done  frequently  by  philoso 
phers,  the  greatest  confusion  results  leading  to  such  self-contradictory  no 
tions  as  "  causa  suz,"  "first  cause,"  "ultimate  cause,"  etc.,  which  lead  either 
to  agnosticism  or  to  mysticism.  For  further  details  see  the  author's  Primer 
of  Philosophy,  the  chapter  on  Causation,  pp.  30-34,  and  Fundamental  Prot- 
Itms,  pp.  29-30. 


202  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

Kant,  following  the  suggestion  of  Hurne,  devoted 
special  attention  to  the  problem  of  causality,  but  he 
solved  it  by  simply  declaring  that  it  wss  a  concept 
a  priori,  and  thus  belonged  to  the  same  class  of 
truths  as  mathematical,  arithmetical,  and  logical  the 
orems.  He  never  attempted  to  explain  its  truth,  let 
alone  to  prove  it,  or  to  demonstrate  its  universality 
and  necessity.  Mathematicians  deem  it  necessary  to 
prove  their  theorems,  but  Kant,  strange  to  say,  neg 
lected  to  deduce  the  law  of  causation  from  simpler 
truths  or  analyse  it  into  its  elements.  If  Kant  had 
made  attempts  to  analyse  causation  for  the  sake  of 
proving  its  validity  after  the  fashion  of  logicians  and 
mathematicians,  he  might,  with  his  keen  insight  into 
the  nature  of  physical  laws  and  natural  sciences,  have 
anticipated  the  discovery  of  the  law  of  the  conserva 
tion  of  matter  and  energy,  and  might  furthermore  have 
been  preserved  from  the  error  of  his  subjectivism 
which  affected  the  whole  system  of  his  thought  and 
twisted  his  philosophy  out  of  shape. 

KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 

In  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  Kant's  position  re 
mains  unintelligible;  we  understand  his  arguments 
and  may  even  approve  the  several  statements  from 
which  they  proceed,  but  we  are  astonished  at  the  bold 
ness  of  the  conclusion,  and  fail  to  be  convinced.  His 
objections  to  the  belief  in  space  and  time  as  objective 
things  hold  good  only  if  space  and  time  are  assumed 
to  be  things  or  objects;  but  not  if  they  are  thought  to 
be  mere  forms  of  objects.  They  are  thinkable  as  forms 
of  thought  not  less  than  as  forms  of  objects.  When 
assumed  to  be  solely  forms  ot  thought  to  the  exclu 
sion  of  the  idea  that  there  are  any  objective  relations 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  203 

corresponding  to  them,  they  become  mysterious  and 
quite  mystical,  and  here  lies  the  reason  why  Kant's 
Critique  of  Pure  Reason  is  actually  mystifying.  He 
bewilders  the  reader.  We  become  acquainted  with 
his  argument  but  do  not  feel  sure  that  we  have  rightly 
apprehended  his  meaning.  In  the  Prolegomena  Kant 
is,  at  least,  not  unintelligible.  The  Prolegomena  are 
not  deductive,  but  inductive.  In  them  Kant  leads  us 
the  way  he  travelled  himself,  and  this  is  the  reason  of 
the  importance  of  the  Prolegomena.  Kant  embodied 
their  contents  in  various  places  into  the  second  edi 
tion  of  his  Critique  of  Pure  Reason.  But  the  passages 
are  scattered  and  lose  the  plainness  and  power  which 
they  possess  in  the  context  of  the  Prolegomena.  Here 
we  are  face  to  face  with  Kant  as  a  man ;  he  gives  us 
a  personal  reply,  as  if  he  were  interviewed  ;  and  while 
we  grant  the  significance  of  transcendentalism  and  the 
truth  of  many  of  his  observations  and  deductions,  we 
can  at  the  same  time  understand  how  he  arrived  at 
errors.  We  can  lay  our  finger  on  the  very  spot  where 
he  went  astray,  and  I  cannot  but  wonder  at  the  cour 
age  of  this  undaunted  thinker  who  abided  by  the  con 
sequences  of  an  apparently  trivial  fallacy,  due  to  the 
neglect  to  investigate  one  feature  of  the  problem  to 
which  he  devoted  many  years  of  his  life  in  profound 
reflexion  and  close  study. 

Kant  was  puzzled  that  we  could  know  anything  a 
priori  concerning  the  formal  constitution  of  things. 
The  celestial  bodies  obey  laws  which  man  develops 
out  of  his  mind.  That  the  highest  (i.  e.,  the  most 
general  or  universal)  laws  of  nature  should  happen  to 
be  the  same  as  the  highest  (i.  e. ,  the  formal)  laws  of 
the  thinking  mind,  and  yet  should  be  of  an  indepen 
dent  origin,  seemed  absurd  to  Kant.  He  saw  only 


204  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

two  possibilities;  either,  he  said,  we  have  derived  our 
formal  knowledge  from  the  things  by  experience,  or 
we  ourselves  have  put  it  into  the  things  to  which  it 
really  does  not  belong.  The  former  possibility  is  ex 
cluded,  because,  says  Kant  (Prolegomena,  §  9),  "The 
properties  of  a  thing  cannot  migrate  into  my  faculty 
of  representation,"  while  on  the  other  hand  the  purely 
formal  truths  are  not  derived  from  experience,  but 
produced  by  the  mind  as  cognitions  a  priori.  Thus, 
Kant  accepts  the  other  horn  of  the  dilemma,  declar 
ing  (Prolegomena,  §  36)  that  our  faculty  of  cognition 
does  not  conform  to  the  objects,  but  contrariwise,  that 
the  objects  conform  to  cognition.  Objects,  he  claimed, 
do  not  in  themselves  possess  form,  but  our  mind  is  so 
constituted  that  it  cannot  help  attributing  form  and 
everything  formal  to  the  object  of  our  experience. 

IDEALITY  NOT  SUBJECTIVITY. 

Now,  it  is  true  that  our  purely  formal  notions  of 
mathematical  and  logical  truths  are  ideal  (made  of 
the  stuff  that  ideas  consist  of),  but  being  purely  formal 
they  are  definitely  determined,  that  is  to  say  that, 
wherever  the  same  constructions  are  made,  either  by 
the  operations  of  other  minds  or  of  natural  conditions 
in  the  facts  of  objective  reality,  they  will  be  found  to 
be  the  same.  Thus,  our  mental  constructions  can  re 
construct  the  processes  and  formations  of  nature,  and 
we  can  learn  to  predetermine  the  course  of  natural 
events. 

Kant  did  not  see  that  form  might  be  a  property  of 
all  existence  and  that,  in  that  case,  the  purely  formal 
in  things  would  be  of  the  same  nature  as  the  purely 
formal  in  man's  mind.  It  is  true  that  the  properties 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  205 

of  things  do  not  migrate  from  the  objects  into  the  sub 
ject,  but  they  make  impressions  upon  the  senses  and 
these  several  impressions  possess  analogies  to  the 
qualities  by  which  they  are  caused.  The  analogies 
between  matter  and  sensation  seem  much  more  arbi 
trary  than  those  between  the  shapes  of  things  and  the 
outlines  of  our  sense-images.  Nevertheless  even  here 
we  grant  that  the  reduction  of  the  latter  to  universal 
laws  is  purely  subjective,  for  there  are  no  laws,  qua 
formulated  laws,  in  the  objective  world,  there  are  only 
uniformities.  But  if  we  understand  by  the  term  law 
a  description  of  uniformities  we  must  see  at  once  that 
there  are  objective  realities  (or  rather  features  of  real 
ity)  corresponding  to  our  correct  notions  of  the  sev 
eral  formal  laws. 

If  the  uniformities  of  nature  are  not  transferred 
to  the  mind  directly,  but  if  the  purely  formal  con 
cepts  nre  developed  independently  of  sense-experience 
a  priori,  how  is  it  possible  that  the  two  present  the 
wonderful  agreement  that  puzzled  Kant? 

Nature  is  throughout  activity,  and  so  is  our  exist 
ence.  Nature  is  constantly  combining  and  separating  ; 
we  observe  transformations;  things  move  about;  and 
their  constituent  parts  change  places.  Similar  ope 
rations  are  inalienable  functions  of  the  mind.  The 
subtlest  analysis  as  well  as  the  most  complicated  com 
position  and  every  investigation,  be  it  ever  so  intri 
cate,  are  mere  combinations  and  separations,  activi 
ties  given  together  with  our  existence. 

The  arguments  of  Kant  by  which  he  proves  the 
apriority  of  purely  formal  laws  must  be  granted  to  be 
true.  The  source  of  all  purely  formal  thought  is  the 
mind,  and  not  sense-perceptions.  They  are  ideal. 
But  the  mind  has  been  built  up  by  experience,  viz., 


206  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

by  sense-impressions  of  different  but  definite  forms, 
and  the  formal  order  of  objective  nature  is  the  mould 
in  which  the  mind  has  been  formed.  The  brute  can 
not  as  yet  analyse  sensations  into  their  forms  and  ma 
terials,  i.  e.,  into  the  purely  relational  and  the  purely 
sensory  features ;  but  man  can  ;  and  when  he  has  ac 
quired  the  power  of  abstraction  he  can  build  models 
of  forms,  exhausting  the  entire  scope  of  all  possible 
cases,  and  these  models  serve  him  as  examples  of  the 
several  analogous  formations  of  nature.  Accordingly, 
our  mental  constitution,  though  a  subjective  construc 
tion,  is  built  up  with  materials  quarried  from  the 
formal  uniformities  of  objective  nature.  Thus  the 
spider  undoubtedly  weaves  his  web  from  his  own  bod 
ily  self,  but  the  materials  have  first  been  deposited 
there  by  nature.  Man's  mind  is  not  less  than  the  spi 
der's  silken  thread,  produced  by,  and  remaining  a  part 
and  an  expression  of,  that  great  All-Being  in  which 
all  creatures  live  and  move  and  have  their  being. 

.There  is  this  difference  between  the  spider's  web 
and  formal  thought :  the  former  consists  of  matter, 
the  pure  forms  of  mathematical,  logical,  and  other 
ideas  are  immaterial ;  they  are  abstracts  made  of  the 
purely  relational  features  of  sense-impressions.  They 
are  ideal,  viz.,  mental  pictures,  and  as  such  they  are 
subjective.  But  they  are  not  purely  subjective.  The 
sensory  part  of  a  retinal  image  is  purely  subjective, 
but  the  formal  preserves  in  a  reduced  size  the  projec 
tion  of  the  shape  of  the  object.  Form  belongs  to  the 
object  as  well  as  to  its  subjective  image,  and  thus  the 
subjective  conception  of  form  possesses  an  objective 
value. 

Everything  ideal  is  subjective,  but  it  need  not  be 
purely  subjective.  Because  the  rational  is  ideal,  it  by 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  207 

no  means  follows  that  it  is  not,  and  cannot  be,  objec 
tive. 

When  \ve  construct  some  purely  formal  configura- 
t'on  with  our  nature-given  mental  operations,  it  will 
I>e  the  same  as  any  other  construction  which  has  been 
made  in  the  same  way,  be  it  in  the  domain  either  of 
things  or  of  other  minds.  Nature  performs  the  same 
operations  which  appear  in  man's  mental  activity. 
Man  being  a  part  of  existence,  what  is  more  natural 
than  that  his  bodily  and  mental  constitution  partakes 
of  the  same  form  as  all  the  other  parts  of  the  world 
that  surrounds  him? 

A  great  and  important  part  of  our  knowledge  con 
sists  of  purely  formal  theorems  ;  they  are  a  priori.  And 
these  purely  formal  theorems  contain  actual  informa 
tion  concerning  the  formal  aspect  of  the  real  world. 
And  why?  Because  they  are  systematic  reconstruc 
tions  of  the  formal  features  of  reality  by  imitating 
operations  of  motion  which  take  place  throughout  the 
universe. 

All  formal  theorems  have  a  general  application, 
hence,  whenever  applicable,  they  afford  a  priori  in 
formation  and  can  be  employed  as  a  key  to  unlock  the 
mysteries  of  the  unknown. 

By  the  rule  of  three  we  calculate  the  distance  from 
the  earth  to  the  sun,  and  map  out  the  paths  of  the 
several  celestial  bodies. 

When  Kant  says:  Our  mind  "dictates"  certain 
laws  to  the  objects  of  experience,  he  uses  a  wrong  ex 
pression  or  takes  a  poetical  license  seriously.  The 
mind  "dictates"  nothing  to  reality.  Reality  includ 
ing  its  form  is  such  as  it  is  independently  of  what  we 
think  it  to  be.  That  which  Kant  calls  dictating  is  a 
mere  determining,  a  description,  implying  at  the  same 


208  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

time  a  foretelling  or  predicting  of  natural  events  which 
(as  we  saw)  is  done  by  constructing  in  our  mind  anal 
ogous  models.  The  agreement  between  our  model 
and  reality  proves  only  that  the  scheme  on  which  the 
model  has  been  constructed  is  correct  ;  it  does  not 
prove  that  the  model  does  any  dictating.  The  model 
dictates  as  little  to  reality  as  a  barometer  dictates  what 
air-pressure  there  is  to  be  in  the  atmosphere. 

THE  FORMAL  AND  THE  SENSORY. 

While  we  must  object  to  Kant's  doctrine  that 
everything  ideal  is  subjective  and  that  what  is  directly 
derived  from  the  mind  cannot  be  objective,  we  must 
not  (with  the  Sensualists)  place  the  formal  and  the 
sensual  on  tht  same  level.  Kant  is  right  that  space 
and  time  are  not  objects  or  things  or  entities  ;  they 
are  forms,  and  as  forms  they  possess  the  quality  of 
being  empty.  There  is  no  particularity  about  them 
anywhere.  Thus,  space  is  space  anywhere;  it  is  not 
like  matter,  denser  here  and  looser  there;  nor  like 
energy,  here  intense,  there  weak.  Considered  in  it 
self,  space  is  the  mere  potentiality  of  existence.  It  is 
a  description  ol.  the  condition  of  granting  motion  to 
move  in  all  directions.  Its  very  indifference  and  ab 
sence  of  anything  particular  implies  uniformity  ;  and 
thus  the  laws  of  potentiality  (i.  e.,  the  qualities  of 
possible  forms)  are  mere  schedules  ;  they  are  empty 
in  themselves,  but  possess  universal  application.1 

The  formal  aspect  of  reality  is  its  suchness;  the 
material  elerrent  is  its  thisness.  All  suchness  can  be 


*ntbi  have  been  felt  by  philosophers  of  all  nations,  and  it  is  sur 
prising  to  £TM?  *.bem  in  the  writings  of  Lao  Tze  and  the  Buddhist  scriptures 
in  both  of  which  the  absence  of  materiality,  the  not-being,  plays  an  impor 
tant  part  aid  *B  endowed  with  religious  sanctity. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  209 

formulated  in  general,  and  even  in  universal,  descrip 
tions ;  all  thisness  is  individual  and  particular.  State 
ments  of  a  general  nature,  such  as  are  formulated  by 
employing  the  methods  of  formal  thought,  are  not 
single  and  concrete  facts,  but  omnipresent  and  eter 
nal  laws  ;  they  are  true  or  untrue,  correct  or  incor 
rect.  Facts  of  thisness  are  always  in  a  special  time 
and  in  a  special  spot  in  space.  They  are  definite  nunc 
and  hie,  not  a  semper  and  ubique.  They  are  not  true 
or  untrue,  but  real  or  unreal. 

The  essential  feature  of  things  is  their  form ;  for 
their  form,  which  is  their  suchness,  viz.,  their  exter 
nal  shape  as  well  as  internal  structure,  constitutes 
their  character,  their  soul,  their  spiritual  significance, 
making  them  what  they  are.  Their  thisness  is  their 
concrete  presence  which  actualises  the  thing  as  a 
stubborn  fact  of  the  material  universe. 

It  is  true  that  the  sense-pictures  in  which  the 
world  is  represented  to  us  are  subjective;  they  are 
appearances  or  phenomena;  it  is  further  true  that 
these  pictures  are  radically  different  from  the  thirgs 
which  they  represent.  The  color-sensation  red  has 
no  similarity  (as  Kant  rightly  observes)  to  the  physi 
cal  qualities  of  vermillion  ;  and  physicists  have  suffi 
ciently  penetrated  into  the  constitution  of  matter  of 
any  kind  (though  most  of  the  problems  remain  still 
unsolved)  to  convince  us  that  matter  as  it  is  in  itself 
is  radically  different  from  the  subjective  picture  as 
which  it  presents  itself  to  the  senses.  But  the  scien 
tist  assumes  form  to  be  objective,  and  all  the  theories 
as  to  the  constitution  of  matter,  in  chemistry  as  well 
as  in  the  several  branches  of  physics,  are  based  on 
the  principle  of  eliminating  the  subjective  element, 
that  is  to  sa37.  the  properly  sensory  ingredients  of  our 


2IO  KANT  S  PHILOSOPHY. 

experience,  by  reducing  them  to  statements  in  purely 
formal  terms,  which  is  done  by  measuring,  by  count 
ing,  by  weighing,  by  defining  their  proportions,  by 
describing  their  shape  and  structure,  by  determining 
their  relations  ;  and  if  we  have  succeeded  in  doing  so, 
we  claim  to  have  understood  the  objective  nature  of 
things.  How  can  Kant's  statement  be  upheld,  that 
the  sensation  red  is  not  an  objective  quality  of  ver- 
million  ?  Is  it  not  because  physics  has  taught  us  that 
difference  of  color  depends  upon  a  difference  of  wave 
length  in  ether  vibration?  Kant's  argument  is  based 
upon  a  tacit  but  indispensable  recognition  of  the  ob 
jectivity  of  form  and  formal  qualities. 

Therefore,  while  granting  that  the  sense-begotten 
world-picture  of  our  intuition  is  subjective  appear 
ance  (cf.  footnote  on  page  232),  we  claim  in  contrast 
to  Kant  that  its  formal  elements  represent  a  feature 
that  inheres  in  existence  as  the  form  of  existence. 

In  making  form  purely  subjective,  Kant  changes 
—notwithstanding  his  protestations — all  ideas,  all 
thoughts,  all  science,  into  purely  subjective  conceits. 
He  is  more  of  an  idealist  than  Berkeley.  Science  can 
be  regarded  as  an  objective  method  of  cognition  only 
if  the  laws  of  form  are  objective  features  of  reality 

THE  MORAL  ASPECT. 

An  incidental  remark  on  the  moral  aspect  of  the 
contrast  between  the  purely  formal  and  the  sensory 
would  not  seem  out  of  place  here.  Man  has  risen  from 
the  sensual  plane  into  the  abstract  realms  of  reason, 
and  morality  becomes  possible  only  by  man's  ability  to 
make  general  principles  the  basis  of  his  actions.  Thus 
it  happens  that  at  a  certain  period  of  man's  develop 
ment  the  sensory  is  regarded  as  the  lower,  and  gen- 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY,  211 

eralisations  with  what  they  imply,  ideals,  maxims, 
abstract  thought,  as  the  higher.  The  sensory  is  thus 
discriminated  against  and  even  denounced  as  the  en 
emy  of  the  spiritual.  Hence  the  dualistic  phase  in 
the  religious  and  philosophical  evolution  of  mankind 
in  which  sensuality  is  branded  as  sin  and  salvation 
sought  in  asceticism,  i.  e.,  the  mortification  of  the 
body. 

We  must  consider,  however,  that  the  contrast  be 
tween  form  and  matter,  general  law  and  particular 
existence,  the  ideal  and  sensory,  spirit  and  matter, 
does  not  imply  a  contradictory  antithesis,  let  alone 
any  hostility  or  exclusivity  of  the  two.  That  the  spir 
itual,  viz.,  the  conception  of  the  purely  formal  with 
reason  and  its  generalisations,  develops  only  on  a 
higher  plane,  cannot  be  used  to  incriminate  the  sen 
sory  and  the  bodily.  On  the  contrary,  the  spiritual 
justifies  the  sensory  and  points  out  the  higher  aims 
which  it  can  attain. 

And  how  indispensable  is  the  sensory  in  religion! 
Consider  but  love,  so  much  insisted  on  by  the  preach 
ers  of  almost  all  higher  faiths.  Is  it  not  even  in  its 
present  form  a  sentiment,  i.  e.,  a  sensory  emotion? 
The  truth  is  that  morality  consists  in  the  sanctifica- 
tion  of  the  sensory,  not  in  its  eradication ;  and  sancti- 
fication  means  setting  aside  and  devoting  to  a  special 
purpose,  to  the  exclusion  of  a  general  use.  Particu 
larity  is  the  nature  of  bodily  existence  and  particu 
larity  demands  exclusiveness.  Any  general  use  of 
bodily  functions  will  prostitute  them.  Reason,  on  the 
contrary,  is  meant  for  general  use  and  can  never  surfer 
from  a  general  application. 

Kant's  conception  of  morality  is  based  upon  rea 
son,  to  the  exclusion  of  sentiment.  Reason  makes 


212  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

action  according  to  principles  or  maxims  possible, 
and  all  those  maxims  are  moral  which  can  become 
universally  established.  Thus  the  basis  of  ethics  is 
the  golden  rule,  pronounced  by  Confucius,  Christ,  and 
other  religious  leaders  of  mankind.  Lao-Tze  says  of 
the  sage:  "His  methods  invite  requital."1 

FORM  BOTH  SUBJECTIVE  AND  OBJECTIVE. 

We  believe  we  have  satisfactorily  explained  the 
problem  of  the  a  priori,  of  the  purely  formal,  which 
puzzled  Kant;  we  have  further  shown  how  and  why 
the  laws  of  purely  formal  thought  agree  with  the 
highest  laws  of  nature  ;  why  being  devoid  of  particu 
larity  they  are  universal  (implying  necessity);  and 
there  remains  only  to  be  pointed  out  that  the  validity 
of  science  rests  upon  the  assurance  of  the  identity  of 
the  subjective  and  the  objective  laws  of  form.  Form, 
being  common  to  both  domains,  the  objectivity  cf 
things  and  the  subjectivity  of  the  mind,  serves  as  a 
bridge  on  which  cognition  can  advance  into  the  un 
known  realms  of  objective  existence,  and  thus  the 
formal  sciences  constitute  our  organ  of  cognition,  the 
objective  reliability  of  which  depends  upon  form  be 
ing  an  objective  feature  of  things. 

It  goes  without  saying  that  all  that  Kant  says 
concerning  their  infinity,  uniqueness,  universality, 
and  necessity  as  being  against  the  belief  that  space 
and  time  are  objects  or  things  holds  good;  it  proves 
that  they  are  forms.  Yet  though  they  must  not  be 
regarded  as  objects,  they  are  objective  ;  they  are  the 
forms  of  intuition  but  also  of  the  objects  intuited. 
Further,  what  Kant  says  (relying  on  symmetry  as  in 

1  Tao-Teh-King,  Chapter  30. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  213 

tuitively  perceived)  to  prove  that  they  are  forms  of 
intuitions  and  not  concepts,  holds  as  well  to  prove 
that  they  are  sighted  forms  of  existence,  not  inter 
nally  hidden  qualities  of  a  stuffy,  thingish  nature  to 
be  distilled  from  sense-perception  in  the  alembic  of 
the  observation  before  its  existence  can  be  known.  It 
is  true  that  the  world  as  it  appears  to  us  is  a  sense- 
woven,  subjective  picture  ;  things  as  we  perceive  them 
are  phenomena.  Further,  our  concepts,  including  the 
world-conception  of  science,  which  is  built  up  with 
the  help  of  the  purely  formal  laws  of  thought,  is  a 
mental  construction  ;  they  are  noumena.  Both  worlds, 
that  of  sense  and  that  of  thought,  are  subjective;  but 
they  represent  reality  ;  the  senses  picture  the  world  in 
the  beauteous  glow  of  sensations,  and  the  mind  de 
scribes  it  in  the  exact  measures  of  formal  determina 
tions  ;  but  the  latter,  if  true,  offers  an  objectively  valid 
model  of  the  constitution  of  things,  explaining  their 
suchness  without,  however,  giving  any  information  as 
to  the  nature  of  reality  in  itself,  i.  e.,  what  matter  is 
in  itself;  whether  it  is  eternal  or  not;  why  it  exists; 
and  if  it  came  into  being,  or  how  it  happened  to  orig 
inate.  It  is  obvious  that  things  are  not  matter,  but 
matter  of  a  definite  form ;  the  form  is  cognisable, 
while  matter  is  simply  the  indication  of  their  concrete 
reality  as  objects  in  the  objective  world. 

SUBJECTIVE  CONSTRUCTIONS  OF  OBJECTIVE 
VALIDITY. 

Kant  in  discriminating  between  empirical  percep 
tion  (viz.,  the  sense  impressions  possessing  only  sub 
jective  validity)  and  experience  (viz.,  the  product  of 
sense-impressions  worked  out  by  the  a  priori  methods 
of  pure  reason  imparting  to  our  judgments  universal- 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

ity  and  necessity)1  goes  far  in  refuting  himself  and  his 
pet  theory.  He  speaks  of  universality  and  necessity 
as  the  only  means  by  which  the  subjective  elements 
can  become  objectively  valid.  He  claims,  e.  g.,  to 
"have  amply  shown  that  they  (the  concepts  of  the 
pure  understanding,  causality,  including  also  mathe 
matics,  etc.)  and  the  theorems  derived  from  them  are 
firmly  established  a  priori,  or  before  all  experience, 
and  have  their  undoubted  objective  value,  though  only 
with  regard  to  experience." 

If  the  concepts  of  the  pure  understanding  have 
objective  value,  why  are  they  not  objective?  Why 
must  they  be  regarded  as  purely  subjective?  We 
grant  the  strength  of  Kant's  argument  that,  being  un 
equivocally  creations  of  the  mind  independent  of 
sense-experience,  or,  as  Kant  calls  them,  a  priori. 
they  are  subjective.  But  is  not  the  question  legiti 
mate  that  they  may  be  at  once  subjective  and  objec 
tive?  Kant  disposes  of  this  question  too  quickly,  and 
here  lies  his  mistake:  instead  of  investigating  how 
certain  uniformities  of  law  may  be  at  once  indigen 
ously  subjective,  i.  e.,  originated  by  purely  mental 
operations,  and  at  the  same  time  objective,  i.  e.,  ac- 
tualised  by  the  operations  of  material  bodies  in  the 
concrete  world  of  real  existence,  he  jumps  at  the  con 
clusion  that  all  things  ideal  are  necessarily  purely 
subjective.  The  ideal,  viz.,  all  that  belongs  to  the 
realm  of  ideas,  is  subjective,  but  it  has  objective  va 
lidity,  and  that  which  gives  it  objective  validity  is  the 
mind's  power  of  forming  universal  and  necessary 
judgments.  In  fact,  the  terms  universal  and  neces 
sary  would  have  no  sense  if  they  were  limited  to  the 
realm  of  subjectivity  and  if  objective  validity  did  not 

1  Prolegomena,  §  2  ff. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  215 

imply  true  objectivity.  Hence  our  aim  is  to  explain 
the  correspondence  between  the  subjective  and  the 
objective,  and  we  come  to  the  conclusion  that  the 
a  priori  judgments  are  based  upon  the  conditions  of 
pure  form,  and  form  is  a  quality  of  the  object  as  well 
as  of  the  subject. 

Thus  while  Kant's  doctrine  implies  that 

the  forms  of  intuition  (space  and  time)  and  the 
formal  laws  are  a  priori  in  the  mind  ;  therefore 
they  are  purely  subjective  and  the  intuiting  and 
thinking  subject  transfers  them  upon  the  objec 
tive  world ; 
our  position  is  the  reverse. 

What  Kant  calls  a  priori  is  purely  formal;  there 
fore  the  mind  can  produce  its  laws  and  theorems  by 
purely  mental  operations,  yet  at  the  same  time,  being 
purely  formal,  they  apply  to  objective  reality  as  the 
formal  conditions  of  all  objects,  and  thus  the  opera 
tions  of  objects,  as  far  as  their  formal  conditions  are 
concerned,  bear  a  close  analogy  to  the  a  priori  theo 
rems. 

We  construct  the  purely  formal  in  our  mind,  but 
we  do  not  create  it.  Nor  are  the  propositions  of 
mathematics  a  quality  of  space.  We  do  not  deduce 
the  Pythagorean  theorem  from  space,  but  we  con 
struct  a  right-angled  triangle  and  investigate  the  re 
suits  of  our  construction.  Accordingly  the  theorems 
thus  evolved  are  products  of  our  mental  operations 
executed  on  conditions  given  in  our  space  conception. 
There  are  no  mathematical  theorems  in  the  stellar 
universe,  but  there  are  conditions  in  the  starry  heav 
ens  which  make  it  possible  to  calculate  distances  or 
other  relations  with  the  help  of  arithmetical  computa 
tions  and  geometric  constructions.  And  the  condi- 


216  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

tions  which  make  this  possible  can  only  be  the  objec 
tivity  of  form  implying  that  the  a  priori  laws  of 
subjective  form  as  constructed  in  our  mental  models 
possess  an  objective  validity. 

THE  OBJECTIVE  ANALOGUES  OF  MENTAL  CON 
STRUCTIONS. 

Zeno's  paradox  and  the  difficulties  which  Clifford 
found  in  the  continuity  conception  of  space,  it  seems 
to  me,  arise  from  a  direct  identification  of  the  mental 
construction  of  space  with  the  objective  formal  fea 
tures  of  things  that  constitute  what  may  be  called  ob 
jective  space.  Objective  space  is  an  inherent  quality 
of  things  as  the  relational  of  their  parts  and  is  not,  as 
in  subjective  space,  a  construction.  The  path  of  a 
body  can  be  represented  by  a  mathematical  line,  and 
aline  is  infinitely  divisible ;  but  for  that  reason  it  is 
not  composed  of  infinite  parts.  Nor  has  a  moving 
body  to  construct  a  line  of  an  infinite  number  of  in 
finitely  minute  parts  by  adding  them  piecemeal.  The 
mental  analysis  and  construction  of  a  line  is  different 
from  traversing  it.  For  moving  over  a  definite  stretch 
of  ground  it  is  not  necessary  to  go  through  the  pro 
cess  of  separately  adding  the  imaginary  infinitely 
small  parts  of  which  it  is  supposed  to  consist  and  into 
which  it  may  be  divided.  It  has  not  actually  been 
divided,  it  is  only  infinitely  divisible. 

It  is  true  that  time  (as  time)  is  purely  subjective, 
but  there  is  a  reality  that  corresponds  to  time.  Time 
is  the  measure  of  motion.  We  count  the  running  sand 
of  the  hour-glass,  we  divide  the  face  of  the  sun-dial, 
we  build  a  clock  to  determine  the  lapse  of  time. 
There  is  no  time  (as  time)  in  the  objective  world, 
but  there  are  motions,  such  as  the  revolutions  of  the 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  217 

earth  round  its  axis,  or  round  the  sun,  and  these  mo 
tions  possess  succession  with  definite  duration,  ren 
dering  time,  viz.,  their  determination,  possible.  Dura 
tion  with  succession  of  events  in  the  world  of  things 
is  the  objective  equivalent  of  time.  The  measurement 
of  time  is  a  subjective  device. 

The  same  is  true  of  space  as  a  conception  of  the 
extended  world  of  things.  There  is  no  space  concep 
tion  in  things,  but  bodies  are  extended ;  and  their  re 
lation  among  themselves  is  an  arrangement  of  in 
numerable  juxtapositions.  Extension,  juxtaposition, 
direction  of  motion,  is  the  objective  quality  of  things 
that  corresponds  to  the  purely  mental  concept  of 
space. 

The  untrained  and  philosophically  crude  man 
transfers  subjective  conceptions  of  things  directly 
upon  the  objective  world.  He  speaks  of  light  and 
colors,  of  sounds,  of  time  and  numbers  and  things  as 
existing  outside  of  his  mind;  but  a  close  inspection  of 
the  origin  of  mind  will  teach  us  to  discriminate  be 
tween  sound  and  air  waves,  between  colors  and  the 
cause  of  colors  (produced  by  a  commotion  in  the 
ether, — a  reality  whose  existence  is  directly  imper 
ceptible  and  can  only  be  deduced  indirectly  by  argu 
ment).  We  shall  learn  by  reflexion  that  geometrical 
lines  are  purely  mental  constructions,  but  that  the 
paths  of  the  stars  possess  qualities  (viz.,  all  those 
which  depend  upon  purely  formal  conditions)  that 
closely  correspond  to  the  conic  sections  of  mathe 
matics. 

Further,  it  becomes  obvious  that  our  division  of 
the  world  into  separate  things  is  artificial,  for  things 
are  only  clusters  of  predicates  which  impress  us  as 
being  units.  The  truth  is  that  the  world  is  so  consti- 


218  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

tuted  as  to  render  a  perfect  separation  impossible. 
Things  are  in  a  perpetual  flux,  and  the  limits  between 
them  are  arbitrary.  As  the  whole  atmosphere  and  its 
pressure  belong  to  our  lungs,  so  the  gravity  of  the  sun 
is  an  integral  part  of  the  weight  of  the  earth.  Thus 
we  can  truly  say  that  there  are  no  separate  things  ex 
cept  in  our  minds  where  they  are  artificial  divisions 
invented  for  the  practical  purpose  of  describing  the 
world,  of  mapping  out  its  parts,  of  comprehending 
its  actions  and  having  a  means  of  adjusting  ourselves 
to  our  surroundings. 

Logic  is  purely  mental,  but  there  is  something  in 
the  objective  world  that  tallies  with  logic  ;  we  call  it 
natural  law,  but  the  term  law  is  misleading.  There 
are  no  laws  in  nature,  but  only  uniformities  resulting 
from  the  condition  that  the  purely  formal  is  the  same 
everywhere  and  that  the  same  formal  conditions  will 
produce  the  same  formal  effects. 

Purely  formal  laws  are  universally  valid  only  as 
purely  formal  laws.  Twice  two  will  be  four  in  all 
arithmetical  systems  of  any  possible  rational  being, 
and  the  statement  is  universally  valid  so  far  as  pure 
forms  are  concerned.  If  we  deal  with  actualities  pos 
sessed  of  additional  qualities  where  multiplication 
ceases  to  have  its  strict  mathematical  sense,  the  state 
ment  will  no  longer  be  tenable.  The  accumulation  of 
power  on  a  definite  occasion  may  have  results  that 
cannot  be  calculated  by  addition  or  multiplication. 
The  associated  wealth  of  twice  two  millions  may  far 
exceed  four  millions ;  and  twice  one  half  will  never  be 
one  when  we  deal  with  living  organisms.  All  this  is 
conceded.  Ideal  operations  are  purely  mental  and  as 
such  subjective,  but  for  all  that  they  possess  objec 
tive  validity  which  implies  that  there  are  objective 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  219 

features  exhibiting  close  analogies,  by  being  products 
of  a  fundamental  sameness  of  conditions.  This  funda 
mental  sameness  is  the  universality  of  form  which  is 
common  to  both  the  domain  of  the  objective  world 
and  the  ideal  realm  of  the  mind,  the  thinking  subject 
There  are  neither  categories  nor  classes  in  the  ob 
jective  world,  but  the  different  modes  of  existence  are 
classified  by  sentient  beings  and  the  scheme  of  the 
classification  is  the  result.  A  reflexion  upon  our  modes 
of  thought  objectifies  them  as  modes  of  existence. 
The  Platonic  ideas,  i.  e. ,  the  eternal  types  of  the  vari 
ous  beings,  do  not  possess  a  concrete  existence  as  do, 
e.  g.,  the  moulds  of  a  potter,  but  there  are  uniformi 
ties  among  the  living  forms  which  are  obviously  ap 
parent.  The  doctrine  of  evolution  proves  that  the 
lines  of  division  between  the  types  of  beings  are  not 
so  distinct  in  reality  as  they  seem  to  be,  and  before  a 
strictly  scientific  inspection  they  fade  away  as  imag 
inary;  yet  they  remain  and  are  indispensable  for  our 
method  of  classification  ;  and  the  unities  which  they 
represent  justify  us  in  speaking  of  objective  features 
as  corresponding  to  the  mental  conception  of  Platonic 
ideas. 

THE  ORIGIN  OF  GENERALISATIONS. 

The  sense-impressions  of  things  are  registered  ac 
cording  to  their  difference  of  form.  Every  sense-im 
pression  runs  along  in  the  groove  prepared  for  it  by  a 
former  sense-impression.  Thus  the  same  is  registered 
with  the  same,  and  similar  ones  are  correlated.  The 
result  is  a  systematisation  of  sensory  impressions,  and 
the  relations  that  obtain  in  this  system  which  is  built 
up  in  the  natural  course  of  growth,  may  appropriately 
be  compared  to  the  pigeon-holes  of  a  methodically 


220  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

arranged  cabinet.  The  difference  between  the  cabinet 
with  pigeon-holes  and  the  human  mind  is  this,  that 
the  former  is  artificial,  the  latter  natural.  The  human 
mind  with  its  rationality  has  been  developed  accord 
ing  to  mechanical  law  and  the  classification  of  sense- 
impressions  is  done  by  it  as  automatically  as  the  dis 
tribution  of  the  different  letters  in  a  type-distributing 
machine. 

Our  ideas,  our  names  of  things,  our  system  of 
classification  is  purely  subjective,  but  there  is  an  ob 
jective  analogue  of  the  eternal  types,  which  consists 
in  the  uniformities  of  all  possible  formations.  This  is 
true  of  living  creatures  as  well  as  of  machines  and 
other  concepts  of  human  fancy.  In  the  domain  of 
invention  we  know  very  well  that  the  inventor  some 
times  creates  a  combination  of  parts  never  actual- 
ised  before  on  earth  ;  but  the  inventor  is  a  finder:  he 
is  as  much  a  discoverer  as  Columbus  who  found  a 
new  continent,  or  the  scientist  who  succeeds  in  formu 
lating  an  unknown  law.  America  existed  before  Co 
lumbus,  the  law  of  gravitation  held  good  before  New 
ton,  and  the  idea  of  a  steam  engine  was  a  realisable 
combination  before  James  Watts.  It  is  a  feature  of 
objective  existence  that  certain  functions  can  be  per 
formed  in  perfectly  definite  interrelations.  Such  con 
ditions  which  are  actualised  by  a  certain  combination 
and  disappear  as  soon  as  the  combination  is  destroyed, 
are  the  objective  features  in  things  which  justify  the 
subjective  idea  of  unities  finding  expression  in  con- 
cepts  of  things  and  beings. 

THE  IDEAS  OF  PURE  REASON. 

Kant  grants  the  objective  applicability  of  the  cate 
gories  but  he  denies  the  validity  of  the  ideas  of  pure 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  221 

reason,  especially  the  cosmological,  the  psychological, 
and  the  theojogical  idea.  We  are  unable  to  follow 
Kant  and  are  inclined  to  consider  his  three  ideas  of 
Pure  Reason  in  the  same  light  as  time  and  space  and 
the  categories.  The  concept  of  unity  is  not  a  mere 
assumption  but  it  has  its  correspondent  analogue  in 
reality1  and  has  its  practical  use;  only  we  must  be 
ware  of  treating  unities  as  concrete  objectivities,  as 
separate  and  discrete  entities,  as  things  in  themselves 
which  have  an  objective  existence  apart  from  and  in 
dependently  of  their  constituent  parts.  Thus  the  soul 
of  man  is  as  real  on  the  assumption  of  an  ego  entity 
as  on  the  theory  of  its  denial.  Life  is  as  true  whether 
or  not  vitalism  can  be  established.  The  world  is  a 
great  interrelated  system,  whether  or  not  the  uniform 
ities  of  nature  are  called  laws.  There  is  a  creation 
of  the  world,  a  formation  of  its  life,  a  dispensation 
of  its  destinies,  taking  place,  whether  or  not  this  ulti 
mate  norm  of  being  be  called  God;  the  facts  of  the 
cosmic  order  remain  the  same  on  the  assumptions  of 
both  theism  and  atheism.  But  obviously,  this  deci 
sion  is  not  an  endorsement  of  Kant's  antinomies,  but 
an  explanation  of  his  reasons  for  formulating  them. 

While  we  grant  that  there  is  a  reality  correspond 
ing  to  Kant's  three  ideas  of  pure  reason,  we  do  not 
mean  to  say  that  there  is  a  God  such  as  the  crude  be 
lief  of  an  untrained  mind  represents  him  to  be,  nor 
further  that  there  is  a  soul  such  as  it  is  assumed  to 
exist  in  the  annals  of  superstition,  nor  finally  that  the 
crude  notions  of  a  cosmos,  the  limits  of  the  world  or 
its  infinitude,  its  composition,  its  determinedness,  and 


IThus  not  only  all  organisms  are  unities,  but  also  steam-engines,  dy 
namos,  or  any  machinery  that  would  not  work  unless  it  were  constructed  of 
interacting  parts  in  a  definite  way. 


222  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

its  absolute  existence  should  be  such  as  abstract  rea 
son  might  arbitrarily  construct:  we  only  mean  to  say 
that  there  are  factors  in  life  which  caused  man  to  con 
struct  such  mental  images  or  ideas  as  are  called  God, 
soul,  and  world.  The  ideas  may  be  wrong,  but  the 
factors  which  produced  them  are  real,  and  the  duty 
devolves  upon  theology,  psychology,  and  cosmology 
to  eliminate  error  and  bring  out  the  truth. 

My  objection  to  Kant's  doctrine  is  not  an  objection 
to  his  terminology  nor  to  idealism  in  general.  We 
may  form  our  world-view  in  an  idealistic  as  well  as  a 
realistic  nomenclature.  Object  may  mean  either  the 
sense-woven  picture  or  the  outside  thing  which  it  sig 
nifies.  We  may  say  that  the  objective  world  is  ideal, 
for  such  it  is,  meaning  by  objects  the  things  as  we  see 
them.  We  may  say  that  the  objective  world  is  real, 
meaning  by  objects  the  actual  things  represented  in 
our  sense-images.  The  nomenclature  of  a  philosoph 
ical  system  is  important  but  it  is  arbitrary.  We  may 
criticise  it  as  impractical,  but  we  cannot  on  its  account 
reject  a  philosophy  as  untrue. 

REALISM  OR  IDEALISM. 

We  object  to  Kant's  doctrine  of  limiting  form  to 
the  subject  and  thus  denying  the  objective  value  of 
the  ideal.  W7e  may  define  terms  as  we  please-but  we 
must  remain  consistent.  If  the  objects  are  ideal,  I 
gladly  grant  that  the  forms  of  the  objects  are  ideal; 
but  for  all  that,  being  forms  of  the  objects,  they  are 
objective,  as  much  as  the  objects  themselves. 

The  sense-woven  pictures  of  things,  though  sub 
jective  images,  are  the  realities  of  life,  and  our  con 
cepts  of  things  are  symbols  of  them  in  terms  of  their 
formal  features  expressed  according  to  schedules 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  223 

which  we  construct  a  priori.  Time  and  space,  the 
forms  of  our  sense- world  (of  our  Ansekauung)9  accord 
ingly  are  as  real  as  these  things,  and  I  cannot  say  that 
the  things  themselves  are  real  while  the  forms  of 
things  are  purely  ideal,  i.  e.,  not  real. 

Schopenhauer,  a  one-sided  but  nevertheless  one  of 
the  most  prominent  and  faithful  disciples  of  Kant,  de 
fends  Kantian  idealism  against  the  misinterpretations 
of  the  so-called  realists  in  these  sentences  : 

"  In  spite  of  all  that  one  may  say,  nothing  is  so  persistently 
and  ever  anew  misunderstood  as  Idealism,  because  it  is  interpreted 
as  meaning  that  one  denies  the  empirical  reality  of  the  external 
world.  Upon  this  re?ts  the  perpetual  return  to  the  appeal  to  com 
mon  sense,  which  appears  in  many  forms  and  guises  ;  for  example, 
as  an  '  irresistible  conviction  '  in  the  Scotch  school,  or  as  Jacobi's 
faith  in  the  reality  of  the  external  world.  The  external  world  by 
no  means  presents  itself,  as  Jac  ;bi  declares,  upon  credit,  and  is 
accepted  by  us  upon  trust  and  faith.  It  presents  itself  as  that 
which  it  is,  and  performs  directly  what  it  promises."1 

THE  SUBJECT  AS  ITS  OWN  OBJECT. 

The  quarrel  between  the  idealists  so  called  and  the 
realists  of  Jacobi's  stamp  is  purely  a  question  of  termi 
nology.  It  is  a  vicious  circle  to  ask  whether  the  real 
is  real;  the  question  is,  "What  do  we  understand  by 
real?"  Now  we  agree  with  Kant  in  accepting  An- 
schauung  as  real.  Our  perceptions  are  the  data  of 
experience,  they  are  the  facts  of  life  about  which  there 
is  no  quibbling  and  the  question  of  unreality  originates 
only  in  the  realm  of  abstract  thought,  viz.,  in  the  do 
main  of  interpretation.  Perceptions  are  classified  ; 
perceptions  of  the  same  kind  are  subsumed  under  the 
general  conception  of  their  class  and  if  a  perception 
is  misinterpreted,  our  notion  concerning  it  is  errone- 

1  From  Schopenhauer's  The  World  as  Will  and  Idea. 


224  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

ous.     An  after-image  is  as  real  as  the  original  pei 
ception,  but  it  is  called  an  illusion  when  it  suggests 
the  presence  of  an  object ;  in  other  words  when  its 
cause  is  misinterpreted. 

Perceptions  accordingly  are  what  we  define  as 
real,  and  space  and  time  are,  abstractly  stated,  the 
forms  of  perception.  Time  and  space,  accordingly, 
are  as  real  as  perceptions. 

Now  we  may  ask  what  are  the  objects  of  the  per 
ceptions,  defining  objects  this  time  not  as  the  sense- 
woven  images  of  our  perception  inside  our  senses, 
but  as  the  external  presences  which  are  supposed  to 
cause  them.  Since  it  is  impossible  here  to  enter  into 
a  detailed  epistemological  discussion  of  the  subject, 
we  state  the  answer  for  brevity's  sake  dogmatically  as 
follows:  The  objects  (viz.,  the  external  presences 
which  are  supposed  to  cause  perceptions)  are,  ulti 
mately,  i.  e.,  in  their  inmost  constitution,  of  the  same 
nature  as  are  the  perceptions  themselves.  The  per 
ceptions  in  their  totality  are  called  the  subject — which 
is  a  sentient  body,  an  intricate  organism  consisting 
of  different  organs  of  sense  and  a  superadded  organ 
of  thought  for  preserving  the  sense-images,  collating 
them,  classifying  them,  and  interpreting  them.  We 
are  a  system  of  perceptions  and  impulses,  guided  by 
memories  and  thoughts,  but  we  represent  ourselves 
in  our  own  perception  as  a  body  in  time  and  space. 
Thus  our  representation  of  ourselves  is  our  self-per 
ception,  i.  e.,  a  representation  of  the  subject  as  its 
own  object,  and  our  self-perception  is  as  real  as  are 
perceptions  in  general.  Succession  of  sense-impres 
sions  and  reactions  thereupon,  accordingly,  form  part 
and  parcel  of  our  subject  as  its  own  object ;  and  in  the 
same  way,  juxtaposition  of  organs  is  an  attribute  of 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  225 

our  self,  not  as  it  is  as  a  subject  in  itself,  but  of  our 
self  as  it  represents  itself  as  its  own  object.  Other 
objects  are  in  the  same  predicament  and  partake  of 
the  same  nature.  If  time  and  space  are  the  forms  of 
the  objectified  subject,  viz.,  of  our  own  bodily  exist 
ence  we  have  good  reasons  to  ascribe  objectivity  to 
the  facts  from  which  the  ideas  of  time  and  space  are 
derived,  viz.,  to  extension  and  succession. 

THE  OBJECTIVE  ORIGIN  OF  SPACE  AND  TIME. 

It  is  true  that  the  factors  which  generate  in  the 
mind  our  conceptions  of  time  and  space,  together  with 
the  entire  formal  aspect  of  being,  lie  in  the  subject,  in 
the  sentient  thinking  being,  but  they  lie  not  in  the  ab 
stract  subject  in  itself,  not  in  the  subjectivity  of  the 
subject,  not  in  the  quality  of  the  subject  which  re 
mains  when  all  other  qualities,  i.  e.,  the  objective 
features  of  its  own  actualisation  as  a  concrete  being, 
are  omitted  by  the  process  of  abstraction,  i.  e.,  when 
they  have  been  cancelled  in  thought.  The  subject  in 
itself  will  be  found  to  be  an  empty  generalisation 
which  contains  nothing  but  a  product  of  our  analysis 
of  perception,  the  bare  idea  of  the  perceiving  in  con 
trast  to  the  perceived.  It  contains  nothing  either  a 
priori  or  a  posteriori ;  merely  itself,  the  shadow  of  a 
thing.  But  the  actual  subject,  which  is  an  object  in 
the  objective  world,  exists  somewhere  in  space  and  in 
a  given  time.  It  moves,  i.  e.,  it  changes  its  position. 
It  consists  of  juxtaposed  organs  and  its  experiences 
exhibit  a  definite  succession,  each  act  having  its  own 
definite  duration.  Therefore  we  do  not  hesitate,  when 
drawing  a  line  of  demarcation  between  the  subjective 
and  the  objective  features  of  the  thinking  subject,  to 
include  its  form  together  with  its  bodily  objectivation 


226  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

in  the  realm  of  objectivity.  In  this  way  it  happens 
i hat  time  and  space  may  be  called  subjective,  because 
the  objectified  subject  finds  them  a  priori  in  itself,  but 
their  ultimate  root  lies  in  the  domain  of  objectivity, 
and  we  can  therefore  just  as  well  call  them  objective, 
because  they  are  the  forms  of  the  objective  world  and 
originate  in  the  subject  only  because  it  is  an  object 
belonging  to  the  objective  world. 

UNIVERSALITY  DUE  TO  SYSTEMATISATION. 

Kant  was  puzzled  mainly  by  the  subjective  aprio 
rity  of  the  laws  of  time  and  space  and  of  all  other  for 
mal  relations,  but  this  puzzling  apriority  is,  closely 
considered,  nothing  but  their  general  applicability  to 
all  possible  experience,  which  is  due  to  the  fact  that 
all  formal  relations  admit  of  systematisation.  Formal 
possibilities  can  be  exhausted  and  purely  formal  state 
ments  apply  to  all  pure  forms.  Hence  they  possess 
universality,  and  universality  admits  of  no  exception, 
hence  it  implies  necessity,  which  involves  a  priori  ap 
plicability. 

It  is  true  (as  Kant  says)  that  purely  formal  knowl 
edge  is  empty;  but  we  know  at  the  same  time  that 
the  purely  formal  knowledge  gives  system  to  the  em 
pirical,  to  the  sense-given  facts  of  our  experience.  If 
we  could  not  classify  sense-impressions,  they  would 
remain  a  useless  chaos,  and  human  reason  would  not 
have  developed.  Kant  expresses  this  truth  by  say 
ing  that  the  sensory  impressions  without  the  guidance 
of  the  purely  formal  are  blind. 

But  as  the  formative  norms  of  the  objective  world 
shape  things  and  make  them  such  as  they  are,  our 
formal  cognition  classifies  sense-impression  according 
to  their  forms  and  thus  makes  a  knowledge  of  objects 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  227 

possible.  Our  formal  cognition  is  not  the  cause  of 
the  objective  uniformities  (as  Kant  suggests)  but  one 
of  their  applications  only,  being,  as  it  were,  their  own 
reflexion  in  the  consciousness  of  a  sentient  being.  By 
be,ng  systematised  in  the  shape  of  formulas,  they  ap 
pi}1  a  priori  to  experience  and  become  in  this  way  a 
key,  with  the  help  of  which  we  can  unlock  the  closed 
doors  of  the  mysteries  of  nature  and  decipher  the 
riddles  of  the  universe. 

THE  REAL  AND  THE  SUPERREAL. 

We  may  call  the  eternal  norms  of  existence  which 
condition  the  formation  of  things  "being"  or  "Sfin" 
and  the  concrete  actualisation  of  the  types  of  being 
their  "becoming,"  Werdtn  or  Dasein.  We  become 
acquainted  with  the  norms  of  existence,  part  of  which 
are  formulated  as  natural  laws,  by  abstraction  and 
generalisation,  but  for  that  reason  they  are  not  mere 
glittering  generalities,  abstract  nonentities,  or  unreal 
inventions,  but  significant  features  of  objective  exist 
ence,  depicting  not  accidental  but  necessary  uniformi 
ties.  While  we  concede  that  the  world  of  becoming 
is  real,  we  must  grant  that  the  realm  of  being  is  super- 
real.  Both  Sfin  and  Wcrden,  Being  and  Becoming, 
are  real ;  but  the  reality  of  the  two  is  different  in  kind. 
The  latter's  reality  is  actualisation,  the  reality  of  the 
former  is  eternality.  Thus  the  former  is  immutable, 
the  latter  a  perpetual  flux.  The  fleeting  realities  of 
sense  are  definite  objects  in  the  objective  world,  but 
the  norms  of  eternal  being  are  the  formative  factors 
which  shape  them. 

Obviously  the  eternal  norms  of  existence,  which 
are  identical  with  the  purely  formal  laws  constituting 
the  cosmic  order,  though  not  material  facts,  are  the 


228  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

most  effective  presences  of  the  world.  They  are  not 
only  real,  they  are  superreal.  They  remain  the  same 
whether  realised  or  not  in  the  actual  world.  They 
produce  the  cosmic  order,  render  the  rise  of  rational 
beings  possible,  they  are  the  condition  of  the  intelli 
gibility  of  things,  they  are  the  prototype  of  mind  and 
spirituality,  they  are  the  corner-stone  of  both  science 
and  ethics  and  constitute  Kant's  mundus  intelligibilis — 
the  realm  of  spiritual  being  ;  Swedenborg's  sphere  of 
spirits,  of  angels,  and  archangels ;  the  kingdom  of 
God,  to  be  realised  on  earth  ;  yea,  God  himself,  for 
God  is  all  these  norms  in  their  totality  and  systematic 
unity.  In  Lao-Tze's  philosophy  it  is  the  eternal  Tao, 
the  world-reason  or  primordial  Logos.  In  Buddhist 
metaphysics  it  corresponds  to  A9vaghosha's  Tatha- 
gatagarbha,  i.  e.,  the  womb  of  Buddhahood  and  the 
origin  of  all  things  ;  to  Amitabha,  the  source  of  all 
light  and  wisdom,  and  also  to  the  deathless,  the  un- 
create,  the  non-corporeal  existence  (ardpcf),  the  Nir 
vana  of  the  older  Buddhists. 

NOUMENA. 

The  data  of  experience  are  sensations,  or  sense- 
perceptions,  which  represent  themselves  as  images  of 
things  in  time  and  space.  The  sensory  element  of 
the  images,  which  is  conditioned  by  the  material  com 
position  of  the  sentient  subject,  is  purely  subjective 
and  need  not  be  uniform.  Thus  we  know  that  colors 
are  perceived  differently  by  different  eyes;  the  color 
blind  see  the  world  like  a  steel  engraving,  or  rather  a 
wash-picture,  gray  in  gray.  To  the  red-blind  red  ap 
pears  green,  to  the  green-blind  red  appears  dark  yel 
low  and  green  pale  yellow.  If  all  men  were  color 
blind,  the  gray  ima^e  would  have  to  be  regarded  as 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  229 

normal.  The  forms  of  things,  too,  are  conditioned  to 
some  extent  by  the  material  composition  of  our  sense- 
organs,  as  much  so  as  the  picture  on  the  sensitive 
plate  of  a  photographer's  camera  depends  upon  the 
lens.  Further,  \ve  see  not  things  as  they  are,  but  as 
they  are  projected  according  to  the  laws  of  perspec 
tive.  But  we  can  from  the  given  data  of  the  projected 
images  and  additional  considerations  of  other  data  of 
experience  reconstruct  the  form  and  structure  of 
tilings  as  they  are  in  space  and  of  the  events  as  they 
and  their  accelerations  take  place  in  time.  This  con 
struction  of  things  is  called  in  Kant's  terminology 
things  as  creations  of  thought,  or  noumena,  and  the 
noumena  are  intended  as  models  of  the  objects  them 
selves,  for  they  mean  to  depict  things  in  their  objec 
tive  nature,  as  they  are  after  the  elimination  of  all 
subjective  elements  of  cognition.  Accordingly  nou 
mena  (as  noumena)  are  scientific  notions,  products 
of  reasoning,  and  subjective  in  a  higher  degree  even 
than  sense-perceptions.  They  are  the  interpretations 
of  the  sense-perceptions  and  are  as  such  ideal,  i.  e., 
representations  not  things.  But  they  represent  things 
as  they  are,  independent  of  the  senses  of  the  sentient 
subject.  Noumena  would  be  unmeaning,  if  they  did 
not  represent  objective  realities,  if  they  were  purely 
fictitious,  if  they  did  not  portray  the  things  as  objects 
in  the  objective  world.  We  may  fitly  call  the  realities 
for  whose  designation  noumena  (i.  e.,  scientific  con 
cepts)  have  been  invented  objects,  or  more  definitely, 
objects  in  themselves. 

They  constitute  the  realm  of  experience,  and  time 
and  space  are  the  generalised  modes  of  their  existence 
by  which  we  determine  their  formal  qualities.  Noth 
ing  is  real  in  the  sense  of  concrete  existence,  except 


230  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

it  be  in  time  and  space.  Accordingly  lime  and  space 
(though  not  objects  but  mere  forms)  are  objective 
qualities  of  things,  and  without  time  and  space  con 
crete  things  cease  to  be  concretely  real  and  become 
either  mere  Ideas  or  nonentities. 

We  may  with  Kant  distinguish  between  thing  and 
thing  in  itself  and  may  understand  by  the  latter  the 
eternal  foundation  of  the  thing,  its  metaphysical  raison 
d'etre,  whatever  that  may  mean  (either  its  Platonic 
idea,  its  eternal  type,  or  the  Schopenhauerian  con 
ception  of  its  "will  to  be,"  or  the  general  and  abstract 
idea  of  its  existence),  but  under  all  conditions  space 
and  time  belong  (as  Kant  says)  to  the  things  as  ap 
pearances,  viz.,  the  things  as  objects  in  the  objective 
world  which  implies  (the  contrary  to  that  which  Kant 
says)  that  they  are  not  purely  subjective,  but  objec 
tive. 

THE  OBJECTIVITY  OF  SPACE  AND  TIME. 

Now  we  may  call  the  perpetual  flux  of  concrete 
objects  « '  appearance,  "and  the  domain  of  eternal  being 
' '  the  real  things  "  :  in  that  case  the  real  things  come  to 
appearance  by  becoming  actual  in  time  and  space.  In 
this  sense  we  agree  with  Kant,  that  time  and  space  are 
real  for  our  experience,  though  not  for  our  experience 
alone,  but  for  any  experience.  Every  sentient  sub 
ject,  in  so  far  as  it  is  sentient,  every  individual  man, 
is  not  a  subject  pure  and  simple,  but  an  actualised 
subject,  an  objectified  thing,  for  all  acts  of  cognition 
are  acts  of  an  objective  significance,  taking  place  in 
the  domain  of  objective  existence,  as  an  interrelation 
between  two  or  several  objects.  One  party  to  this 
interrelation  (viz.,  my  bodily  organisation)  happens 
to  be  the  sentient  and  thinking  subject,  but  that  alters 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  231 

nothing  in  the  case,  for  all  its  actions  take  place  in 
time,  and  the  concrete  corporeality  of  its  organs  is 
somewhere  in  space.  Again  therefore  we  come  to  the 
conclusion  that  space  and  time  appertain  (as  Kant 
says)  to  the  appearances  of  things.  They  appertain  to 
the  subject,  not  in  itself,  but  to  the  appearance  of  the 
subject,  viz.,  to  its  objectivation  ;  accordingly  they  are 
(as  opposed  to  what  Kant  says)  objective,  not  purely 
subjective,  and  may  be  called  subjective  only  in  a  spe 
cial  sense,  viz.,  in  so  far  as  they  appertain  to  the  objec 
tified  subject,  which,  however,  is  an  object  like  any 
other  object  in  the  objective  world.  The  subject  does 
not  transfer  time  and  space  into  the  objective  world, 
but  anything  that  becomes  actual  thereby  makes  its 
appearance  in  time  and  space.  In  other  words,  Time, 
Space,  and  all  the  norms  of  purely  formal  relations, 
are  the  forms  of  any  possible  concrete  existence: 
Whatever  the  metaphysical  raison  d'etre  of  things  may 
be,  the  "why  there  is  anything,"  reality,  when  ac- 
tualiscd,  represents  itself  objectively  as  being  in  time 
and  space.  The  thinking  subject  does  not  represent 
things  in  time  and  space,  but  in  so  far  as  it  is  an  actual 
object  in  the  objective  world,  it  represents  itself  (i.  e., 
it  appears)  in  time  and  space.  So  do  all  other  things  : 
hence  the  concurrence  of  the  formal  notions  of  the 
objectified  subject  with  the  formal  conditions  of  the 
objectified  things  of  our  surroundings.  Kant  says 

(§520: 

"Space  and  time  together  with  the  appear 
ances  in  them  are  nothing  existing  in  themselves 
and  outside  of  my  representations  but  are  them 
selves  only  modes  of  representation."1 

lit  is  very  strange  that  the  same  Kant  who  says  that  space  (viz.,  extf-rt 
sion)  is  only  a  mode  of  representation  dec  rres   (in  §  2)   that  the  sentence 


232 

He  should  have  said  (and  here  we  use  purposely 
Kant's  own  term  « '  appearance  "  *)  : 

Time  and  space  are  modes  of  appearance,  viz., 
of  self-representation. 

Being  modes  of  appearance  they  are  inside  every 
subject  in  so  far  as  it  has  made  its  appearance  in  the 
objective  world.  They  are  in  all  objects  as  those  re 
lational  features  which  determine  the  juxtaposition 
of  things.  It  is  the  actualised  appearance  that  needs 
extension  (i.  e.,  space)  for  the  distribution  of  the  sev 
eral  organs  of  the  thinking  subject.  We  feel  our  limbs 
as  being  in  different  places,  as  moving  about,  as  touch 
ing,  as  separating,  etc.,  and  these  feelings  are  parts 
of  our  soul :  they  are  the  inside  of  the  subject  which 
is  objectified  (or  comes  to  appearance)  in  our  bodily 
existence.  Our  body  (viz.,  our  self  as  appearance)  is 
extended,  and  the  space,  needed  for  it,  is  limited  by 
the  skin.  The  remainder  of  extension  which  accomo- 
dates  the  other  objects  of  the  surrounding  world  is 
designated  as  the  outside ;  and  if  the  extension  within 
our  skin  is  real,  the  outside  must  also  be  real.  Both 
together  constitute  space. 

"bodies  are  extended  "is  analytical;  accordingly  he  regards  extension  or 
space  as  the  essential  feature  of  a  thing,  of  an  object.  Why  then  does  he  not 
recognise  space  as  the  mark  of  objectivism,  which  might  have  led  him  to 
concede  the  objective  nature  of  the  operations  of  the  thinking  subject? 

1  Appearance  or  phenomenon  means  originally  the  picture  of  objects  as 
it  appears  on  the  retina  and  generally  all  the  data  of  sense-perception  ;  but 
the  word  is  used  in  contrast  to  noumenon,  or  abstract  thought,  denoting  the 
concrete  object  as  it  is  given  to  the  senses  distinguished  from  its  general  and 
abstract  idea.  Thus,  the  world  of  appearances  means  the  concrete  world  of 
objects  that  affect  our  senses,  though  the  term  might  be  interpreted  to  stand 
for  the  retinal  picture  as  a  mere  subjective  image  in  contrast  to  the  material 
world  of  objective  reality.  Indeed,  there  are  authors  who  do  use  the  word  in 
the  latter  sense,  while  in  the  minds  of  most  readers  the  two  conceptions  are 
mixed  and  the  former  is  imperceptibly  affected  by  the  latter.  It  would  not  be 
difficult  to  point  out  what  an  interminable  confusion  the  use  of  this  word  has 
produced  in  philosophy. 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.    .  233 

When  Kant  denies  that  space  and  time  are  objec- 
Jve,  he  becomes  confused  and  self-contradictory.  For 
ne  would  either  have  to  say  that  space  and  time  are 
limited  within  the  boundary  of  the  body  of  the  think 
ing  subject,  which  is  nonsense,  or  he  must  attribute 
them  to  the  subject  as  a  thing  in  itself,  which  contra 
dicts  his  own  theory  according  to  which  time  and 
space  do  not  refer  to  things  in  themselves,  but  to  ap 
pearances  only.  Thus  even  from  Kant's  own  premises 
and  when  employing  his  own  terminology  the  theory 
becomes  untenable  that  space  and  time  are  purely 
subjective  attributes.  Their  very  nature  is  objectivity, 
and  if  objects  are  appearances,  time  and  space  as  the 
forms  of  all  appearance  must  be  regarded  as  features 
of  existence  which  in  their  very  nature  are  objective. 
It  appears  that  Kant  was  not  sufficiently  careful  to 
distinguish  between  space-conception,  which  is  sub 
jective,  and  space  itself,  which,  being  the  juxtaposi 
tion  of  things  and  their  parts,  is  objective.  Space- 
conception  originates  from  within  sentient  organisms, 
viz.,  in  the  mind,  by  its  adjustment  to  the  surround 
ing  world  through  the  use  of  its  organs.  Its  ultimate 
sources  are  of  a  physiological  nature  consisting  in  the 
motion  of  the  limbs  and  especially  the  eyes.  This  is 
what  Ernst  Mach  calls  physiological  space.1  Mathe 
matical  space  is  a  higher  abstraction  than  physiolo 
gical  space.  In  mathematical  space  all  incidental  fea 
tures,  the  differences  of  right  and  left,  of  high  and  low, 
etc.,  are  dropped,  and  space  is  regarded  as  homa- 
loidal,  viz.,  as  constituted  alike  throughout.  The 
homaloidality  of  space  is  the  simplest  way  of  depriv 
ing  space  of  all  positive  attributes,  of  rendering  it  the 

ISee  Ernst  Mach's  article  "On  Physiological,  as  Distinguished   from 
Geometrical  Space,"  in  The  Monixt,  Vol.  XL,  No.  3.,  April,  1901. 


234  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

"same"  throughout.  At  any  rate  it  is  a  mental  con 
struction  as  much  as  the  idea  of  a  straight  line  and  all 
geometrical  figures.  The  construction  has  been  made 
without  any  concrete  building  material,  with  mere  men 
tal  operations,  simply  by  proceeding  on  the  assump 
tion  of  logical  consistency,  where  the  same  procedure 
yields  the  same  result.  That  other  space  construc 
tions  are  possible  need  not  concern  us  here.  At  any 
rate,  our  space-conception  is  built  up  in  the  thinking 
subject  by  operations  of  which  it  is  possessed  in  its 
capacity  as  an  object  moving  about  in  the  objective 
world.  Our  space-conception  is  a  noumenon  (a  pro 
duct  of  thought),  and  like  all  noumena,  it  is  intended 
to  describe  features  of  objective  reality;  and  the?e 
features  of  objective  reality  intended  to  be  delineated 
in  our  space-conception  is  objective  space — viz.,  the 
extension  of  the  world  and  of  its  parts,  the  juxtaposi 
tion  of  bodies,  and  the  range  of  directions  all  around 
every  moving  point. 

Our  space-conception  is  subjective,  but  for  that 
reason  space  itself  remains  as  objective  as  any  object 
in  space.  Moreover,  the  data  from  which  our  space- 
conception  has  been  constructed  are  as  objective  as 
are  all  the  acts  and  facts  of  our  bodily  organism, 

THINGS  IN  THEMSELVES. 

Where,  then,  are  the  things  in  themselves,  which, 
according  to  Kant,  remain  unintelligible  ? 

There  is  a  truth  in  the  idea  that  our  mind  is  so 
constituted  as  to  transfer  to  the  phenomenal  world 
its  a  priori  notions  of  time  and  space  and  its  thought- 
forms.  The  world  of  our  senses  which  appears  to  us 
as  the  objective  world  that  surrounds  us.  is  truly  a 
construction  of  our  organs  of  sense  ;  the  construction 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  235 

is  as  necessary  as  is  for  example  the  reflexion  of  a  pic 
ture  in  a  mirror  ;  things  in  themselves  remain  outside. 
In  this  sense  Kant's  doctrine  of  idealism  is  undeniably 
true. 

But  Kant  goes  further  in  saying  that  things  in 
themselves,  meaning  things  viewed  independently  of 
our  sense-perception,  do  not  partake  of  form  and  are 
therefore  unknowable.  But  what  is  knowledge  if  not 
a  correct  description  of  things?  Things  are  mirrored 
in  our  eyes,  and  abstract  notions  are  formed  to  rep 
resent  them  in  mental  symbols.  It  would  be  absurd 
to  expect  that  things  should  bodily  migrate  into  our 
heads. 

It  is  the  ideal  of  science  to  eliminate  the  subjec 
tivity  of  the  thinking  subject  and  construct  a  world- 
picture  in  terms  of  formal  laws,  by  the  guidance  of 
the  several  sciences  of  formal  thought;  this  is  the 
noumenal  world,  the  world  of  thought ;  but  this  nou- 
menal  world  is  nothing  but  a  picture  (more  or  less  ac 
curate)  of  the  objective  world  as  things  are  indepen 
dently  of  sense-perception.  Here  everything  changes 
into  motion  of  a  definite  form  ;  the  rainbow  with  the 
warm  beauty  of  its  colors  becomes  the  reflexion  of 
?ther  waves  of  a  definite  angle  with  definite  wave 
lengths.  Though  the  noumenon  is  a  subjective  con 
struction,  it  is  an  analogue  of  the  objects  as  they  are 
in  themselves,  describing  their  suchness.  Accord 
ingly,  this  would  be  a  cognition  of  things  in  them 
selves,  for  Kant  defines  things  in  themselves  as  the 
ground  which  determines  our  sensibility  to  have  sense- 
perceptions,  or  briefly  the  causes  of  phenomena. 

Cognition  is  nothing  more  nor  less  than  the  con 
struction  of  analogous  symbols  of  things  by  which  we 
can  know  their  nature  for  the  sake  of  determining 


236  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

their  action,  thus  enabling  us  to  direct  the  course  of 
events  by  adaptation  partly  of  ourselves  to  conditions, 
partly  of  our  surroundings  to  our  wants.  Unless  we 
denounce  science  as  a  vagary  of  the  human  mind,  we 
must  grant  that  in  spite  of  the  shortcomings  of  the 
individual  scientist,  the  ideal  of  science  (which  con 
sists  in  describing  things  in  their  objective  existence) 
is  justified,  and  can  be  more  and  more  realised. 

And  what  becomes  of  things  in  themselves? 

If  things  in  themselves  cannot  be  described  with 
the  assistance  of  formal  thoughts,  they  degenerate 
into  dim  chimerical  and  contradictory  notions,  such 
as  unextended  bodies,  or  substances  without  quali 
ties,  or  unmaterial  entities,  or  causes  which  remain 
outside  the  pale  of  causation. 

The  conception  of  things  in  themselves  is  a  vagary 
of  pre-Kantian  metaphysics,  the  empty  shell  of  which, 
as  an  irrational  quantity,  transcendent  and  unknow 
able,  was  by  some  mishap  suffered  to  remain  in  Kant's 
philosophy. 

If  things  in  themselves  mean  objective  things, 
viz.,  things  as  they  are,  independently  of  our  sensi 
bility,  we  must  deny  that  they  are  unknowable.  If 
they  mean  that  which  constitutes  the  essential  char 
acter  of  the  things,  making  them  what  they  are,  they 
will  be  seen  to  be  determined  by  their  suchness;  they 
are  what  Plato  called  the  eternal  types  of  being,  or 
ideas;  and  we  ought  to  call  them  not  "things  in 
themselves,"  but  "forms  in  themselves." 

Schopenhauer  interprets  the  Kantian  conception 
of  things  in  themselves  as  the  metaphysical  raison 
d'etre  of  their  existence,  but  he  denies  that  its  nature 
cannot  be  known  and  discovers  its  manifestation  in 
"the  Will."  According  to  him  it  is  the  Will  that 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  237 

makes  every  one  what  he  is,  and  Schopenhauer's  Will 
is  not  the  physiological  process  of  willing,  the  con 
scious  effort  of  causing  an  idea  to  pass  into  an  act,  but 
the  tendency  to  motion  such  as  it  inheres  in  all  exist 
ence,  in  the  stone  as  gravity,  in  chemicals  as  affinity, 
in  sentient  beings  as  desire.  He  expressly  excludes 
that  feature  which  distinguishes  will  from  unconscious 
motions,  viz.,  intelligence,  and  speaks  of  the  blind 
Will.  The  blind  Will  is  practically  deified  by  him, 
for  it  is  supposed  to  be  above  time  and  space  and 
credited  with  creative  omnipotence.  In  reality  it  is 
nothing  but  the  widest  generalisation  of  motion. 

Clifford  offers  another  interpretation  of  the  term 
'•thing  in  itself,"  viz.,  the  sentiency  of  organised  be 
ings,  constituting  their  subjectivity  and  corresponding 
to  what  in  man  is  called  his  "soul."  But,  again,  this 
subjectivity,  the  spiritual  inside,  is  always  the  sentient 
accompaniment  of  the  organisation,  the  bodily  out 
side  ;  and  its  nature  can  be  determined  by  studying 
the  visible  exponents  of  its  objective  expression  in 
which  it  is  realised.  Thus  Clifford's  things  in  them 
selves  are  as  little  unknowable  as  Schopenhauer's. 

Agnosticism,  the  egg-shell  of  metaphysicism,  pre 
vented  Kant  from  taking  the  last  step  suggested  by 
his  doctrine  of  the  necessity  and  universality  of  the 
laws  of  pure  form.  He  lost  himself  in  contradictions 
and  became  satisfied  with  his  statement  of  the  antino 
mies  of  pure  reason,  according  to  which  we  may  prove 
with  equal  plausibility  that  God  exists  or  that  he  does 
not. 

THE  GOD  PROBLEM. 

If  Kant  had  followed  the  course  which  we  here, 
under  the  guidance  of  the  principles  laid  out  by  him, 


238  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

have  briefly  sketched  out,  his  philosophy  not  only 
would  have  become  less  artificial  and  remained  in 
close  touch  with  the  natural  sciences,  but  it  would 
a'SO  have  helped  theology  to  develop*  purer,  truer, 
and  nobler  religious  ideals.  With  the  egg-shell  of 
agnosticism  on  its  back,  Kantism  was  satisfied  with 
the  existing  state  of  beliefs  and  tilings  ;  nc  t  that  Kant 
endorsed  the  various  irrationalities  cf  the  Christianity 
of  his  day,  the  literalism  of  dogma,  the  implicit  belief 
in  the  very  text  of  the  Bible,  the  Creation  story,  pa 
ternalism  of  the  Prussian  State  Church,  etc.;  he  criti 
cised  them  occasionally  in  mild  terms  ;  but  instead  of 
going  to  work  to  purify  religion  (not  in  the  narrow 
and  prosaic  spirit  of  his  disciples,  the  Rationalists, 
but  with  due  reverence  for  the  poetry  of  dogma  and 
legend,  and  at  the  same  time  with  a  consideration  for 
the  practical  needs  of  the  heart):  he  simply  justified 
them  in  general  terms  on  account  of  their  moral  use 
fulness  in  his  Critique  of  Practical  Reason. 

As  an  instance,  let  us  point  out  his  unsatisfactory 
solution  of  the  God  problem. 

Kant  accepted  in  his  conception  of  God  the  tradi 
tional  views  of  the  Church,  and  discussed  it  as  one  of 
the  several  metaphysical  notions,  the  result  being  that 
the  idea  is  pronounced  to  be  transcendent,  and  we 
can  with  equally  plausible  reasons  both  affirm  and 
deny  his  existence.  It  is  one  of  Kant's  four  antino 
mies  of  Pure  Reason.  But  God  unknown  to  pure 
reason  and  not  discoverable  in  the  domain  of  experi 
ence  and  resuscitated  only  as  a  postulate  of  practical 
reason  is  a  poor  substitute  even  for  the  mythological 
conception  of  the  god  of  the  uneducated  masses.  An 
hypothetical  god  cannot  help;  he  is  sicklied  over 
with  the  pale  cast  of  thought ;  he  is  not  real ;  he  is 


KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY.  239 

paralysed.  I  arn  far  from  blaming  Kant,  who  has 
done  so  much  for  philosophy,  for  not  having  done 
more  and  performed  a  reformer's  work  for  religion ; 
but  I  would  suggest  that  he  might  as  well  from  his 
own  principles  have  investigated  the  nature  of  formal 
laws,  which  in  the  subjective  sphere  of  reason  appear 
as  transcendental  ideas,  and  have  come  to  the  conclu 
sion  that  a  truer  God-conception  could  be  derived 
therefrom,  which  then  would  commend  itself  as  the 
higher  ideal.  The  popular  notions  of  the  several  re 
ligions  and  also  of  a  primitive  theology  are  dim  fore- 
shadovings  of  a  scientific  God-conception,  the  purity 
of  whivh  is  inci^afling  with  the  progress  of  scientific 
truth. 

Thf*  world  •dtfder,  that  purely  formal  law  in  the 
objective  worM  which  forms  and  creates,  shaping  the 
stellar  universe  (as  Kant  set  forth  so  forcibly  in  his 
General  Natural  History  and  Theory  of  the  Heavens}, 
and  rfYealing  itself  in  the  social  development  of  man 
as  the  power  that  makes  for  righteousness,  must  have 
made  its  influence  felt  in  the  life  of  mankind  at  the 
very  beginning,  and  would  naturally,  according  to  the 
practical  needs  of  the  intelligence  of  the  successive 
ages.,  assume  the  shape  of  a  conception  of  God,  more 
or  less  crude  in  the  beginning,  and  more  or  less  phil 
osophical  in  the  mind  of  the  wise.  The  world-order, 
this  superpersonal  spirituality  that  acts  as  the  divine 
dispensation  in  the  world,  is  hyperphysical  (I  pur 
posely  avoid  the  much-abused  term  "supernatural," 
but  I  might  as  well  say  supernatural).  It  is  intrinsi 
cally  necessary,  it  is  omnipresent,  it  is  unerring  in  the 
truth  of  its  various  applications  which  form  as  it  were 
a  gr^nd  system,  comparable  to  the  articulated  differ- 
et  >  ^rr,  of  a  spiritual  organism, — a  personality ;  it 


240  KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 

is  as  unfailingly  just  as  the  law  of  causation  is  rigid  ; 
and  every  God-conception  is  but  an  attempt  at  com 
prehending  its  moral  significance. 

The  fetishist's  notion  of  a  power  to  which  he  must 
conform  is  not  absolutely  wrong.  It  contains  a  truth, 
but  is  alloyed  with  superstitions.  The  idea  of  think 
ing  of  God  as  a  king  of  kings,  as  a  supreme  judge,  is 
more  advanced,  inasmuch  as  God  henceforth  repre 
sents  a  moral  maxim,  the  principle  of  justice  in  the 
world.  The  God-father  idea  of  Christianity  surpasses 
the  theology  of  the  prophets  of  the  Old  Testament, 
but  it,  too,  falls  short  of  the  truth  in  all  its  perfection. 
All  we  have  to  do  is  to  be  serious  in  scientifically 
thinking  the  divine  attributes  of  omnipresence,  of 
eternality,  of  infinitude,  of  omniscience,  of  all-justice, 
of  the  irrefragability  of  law  in  the  physical,  the  psy 
chical,  and  the  social  spheres  of  existence,  which,  re 
flected  in  the  instructive  growth  of  his  conscience, 
become  to  man  the  moral  norm  of  liie,  and  the  ulti 
mate  authority  of  conduct. 

Kant  cited  the  religious  notions  of  the  theology  of 
his  age  before  the  tribunal  of  pure  reason  and  dis 
missed  the  suit  as  offering  no  issue,  leaving  the  ques 
tion  in  the  state  in  which  he  had  found  it.  He  would 
have  served  his  age  better  had  he  worked  out  the 
philosophical  significance  of  the  idea  of  God,  on  the 
basis  of  the  practical  significance  of  his  Transcenden 
talism  ;  he  would  then,  instead  of  leaving  the  problem 
unsolved,  have  boldly  propounded  the  gospel  of  the 
superpersonal  God  as  coming,  not  to  destroy  the  old 
theology,  but  to  fulfil  its  yearnings  and  hopes,  with 
out  in  the  least  doing  violence  to  the  demands  of  crit 
icism  and  scientific  exactness. 


SUPPLEMENTARY  MATERIALS   FOR 

THE  STUDY  OF  KANT'S  LIFE 

AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


INTRODUCTORY  NOTE. 


materials,  culled  from  Kantian  literature,  are  intended 
-L  as  specimens  of  the  various  opinions  which  prevail  concern 
ing  Kant,  and  have  been  arranged  and  added  to  this  book  for  the 
purpose  of  enabling  the  student  to  study  Kant  in  the  impressions 
which  he  made  upon  the  philosophical  public.  The  selection  has 
at  the  same  time  been  offered  with  the  intention  of  giving  a 
brief  synopsis  of  Kant's  work,  at  least  so  far  as  the  systematic  con 
struction,  or  Ausbau,  of  his  transcendental  criticism  is  concerned. 
It  is  understood  that  Kant's  merits  as  a  thinker  and  inquirer  are  not 
limited  to  metaphysics,  but  it  would  have  led  us  too  far,  and  would 
have  swelled  the  book  to  too  bulky  a  size,  without  doing  justice  to 
the  subject,  if  we  had  also  attempted  to  consider  here  Kant's  re 
searches  in  physics,  mechanics,  astronomy,  and  the  other  natural 
sciences.  That  Kant  had  a  clear  idea,  not  only  of  evolution  and  of 
the  descent  of  man  from  lower  forms  of  life,  but  also  of  the  dif 
ficulties  of  the  evolution  theory,  is  well  attested  by  many  remark 
able  passages,  collected  by  Fritz  Schultze1. 

We  have  only  to  add  that  we  have  selected  Windelband  as  a 
representative  historian  of  philosophy,  in  preference,  say,  to  Erd- 
mann  and  Ueberweg,  solely  because  of  the  terseness  of  his  state 
ments.  Schwegler  is  a  Hegelian,  Weber  an  Alsatian  under  French 
influence.  Lange  represents  the  large  class  of  agnostics  who  grant 
that  materialism  is  untenable  as  a  philosophy  but  deem  it  to  be 
the  best  working  hypothesis  in  science.  Schopenhauer  is  one  of 
the  most  original  disciples  of  Kant,  and  set  up  a  philosophy  of  his 
own,  conceiving  the  world  under  the  double  aspect  of  Will  and 
Idea.  He  hates  Hegel  and  all  "  school-philosophy,"  saying  that  he 
himself,  the  true  philosopher,  lives  for  philosophy,  while  the  pro 
fessors  appointed  to  teach  philosophy  live  on  philosophy.  Heine 


\Kant  und  Darwin,  ein  Beitra^  zur  Geschichte  der  Entwzckelungslekre 
Jena,  1875. 


244  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

is  peculiarly  interesting,  being  brilliant  and  cynical  at  the  same 
time.  He  speaks  sometimes  as  if  he  were  an  atheist,  and  again 
advocates  a  theism  verging  on  pantheism.  Theodore  F.  Wright's 
digest  of  Stuckenberg  is  cavilling  and  spiteful.  His  is  the  most 
unfavorable  view  of  Kant,  and  we  quote  it  on  that  account.  Paul- 
sen's  chronological  table  will  be  welcome  as  a  useful  synopsis  of 
the  data  of  Kant's  life.  p.  c. 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  WRITINGS. 

(AFTER  WINDEX-BAND.*) 

TMMANUEL  KANT  was  born  April  22,  1724,  at  Konigsberg, 
J.  Prussia,  the  son  of  a  saddler.  He  was  educated  at  the  Pietistic 
Collegium  Fridericianum,  and  attended  in  1740  the  University  of 
his  native  city  to  study  theology  ;  but  subjects  of  natural  science 
and  philosophy  gradually  attracted  him.  After  concluding  his 
studies,  he  became  a  private  teacher  in  various  families  in  the 
vicinity  of  Konigsberg  from  1746  to  1755  ;  in  the  autumn  of  1755  he 
habilitated  as  Privatdocent  in  the  philosophical  faculty  of  Konigs 
berg  University,  and  was  made  full  Professor  there  in  1770.  The 
cheerful,  brilliant  animation,  and  versatility  of  his  middle  years 
gave  place  with  time  to  an  earnest,  rigorous  conception  of  life  and 
to  the  control  of  a  strict  consciousness  of  duty,  which  manifested 
itself  in  his  unremitting  labour  upon  his  great  philosophical  task, 
in  his  masterful  fulfilment  of  the  duties  of  his  academic  profession, 
and  in  the  inflexible  rectitude  of  his  life,  which  was  not  without 
a  shade  of  the  pedantic.  The  uniform  course  of  his  solitary  and 
modest  scholar's  life  was  not  disturbed  by  the  brilliancy  of  the 
fame  that  fell  upon  his  life's  evening,  and  only  transiently  by  the 
dark  shadow  that  the  hatred  of  orthodoxy,  which  had  obtained 
control  under  Frederick  William  II.,  threatened  to  cast  upon  his 
path  by  a  prohibition  of  his  philosophy.  He  died  from  the  weak 
ness  of  old  age  on  the  i2th  of  February,  1804. 

Kant's  middle  and  later  life  and  personality  has  been  drawn 
most  completely  by  Kuno  Fischer  (Geschtchte  der  neueren  Philo 
sophic,  III.  and  IV.,  3d  ed.,  Munich,  1882);  E.  Arnoldt  has  treated 
of  his  youth  and  the  first  part  of  his  activity  as  a  teacher  (Konigs 
berg,  1882).  See  also  J  H.  W.  Stuckenberg,  Life  of  Kant  (Lon 
don,  1882). 

\History  of  Philosophy.  Translated  from  the  German  by  James  H.  Tufts, 
New  York  :  Macmillan,  1893.  Price  $500.  This  work  is  especially  valuable  as 
a  comparative  treatment  of  the  history  of  thought 


246  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

The  change  which  was  taking  place  in  the  philosopher  toward 
the  end  of  the  seventh  decade  of  the  eighteenth  cemury  appears 
especially  in  his  activity  as  a  writer.  His  earlier  "pre-critical" 
works  are  distinguished  by  easy-flowing,  graceful  presentation, 
and  present  themselves  as  admirable  occasional  writings  of  a  man 
of  fine  thought  who  is  well  versed  in  the  world.  His  later  works 
show  the  laboriousness  of  his  thought  and  the  pressure  of  the  con 
tending  motifs,  both  in  the  form  of  the  investigation,  with  its  cir 
cumstantial  heaviness  and  artificial  architectonic  structure,  and  in 
the  formation  of  his  sentences,  which  are  highly  involved,  and 
frequently  interrupted  by  restriction.  Minerva  frightened  away 
the  graces ;  but  instead,  the  devout  tone  of  deep  thought  and 
earnest  conviction,  which  here  and  there  rises  to  powerful  pathos 
and  weighty  expression,  hovers  over  his  later  writings. 

For  Kant's  theoretical  development,  the  antithesis  between  the 
Leibnizo-Wolffian  metaphysics  and  the  Newtonian  natural  philos 
ophy  was  at  the  beginning  of  decisive  importance.  The  former 
had  been  brought  to  his  attention  at  the  University  by  Knutzen, 
the  latter  by  Teske,  and  in  his  growing  alienation  from  the  philo 
sophical  school-system,  his  interest  for  natural  science,  to  which 
for  the  time  he  seemed  to  desire  to  devote  himself  entirely,  co 
operated  strongly.  His  first  treatise,  1747,  was  entitled  Thoughts 
upon  the  True  Measure  of  Vis  Viva,  a  controverted  question  be 
tween  Cartesian  and  Leibnizian  physicists ;  his  great  work  upon 
the  General  Natural  History  and  Theory  of  the  Heavens  was  a 
natural  science  production  of  the  first  rank,  and  besides  small 
articles,  his  promotion-treatise,  De  Igne  (1755),  which  propounded 
a  hypothesis  as  to  imponderables,  belongs  here.  His  activity  as  a 
teacher  also  showed,  even  on  into  his  later  period,  a  preference  for 
the  subjects  of  natural  sciences,  especially  for  physical  geography 
and  anthropology. 

In  theoretical  philosophy  Kant  passed  through  many  reversals 
(mancherlei  Umkippungcn}  of  his  standpoint.  At  the  beginning 
(in  the  Physical  Monadology}  he  had  sought  to  adjust  the  opposi 
tion  between  Leibniz  and  Newton,  in  their  doctrine  of  space,  by 
the  ordinary  distinction  of  things-in-themselves  (which  are  to  be 
known  metaphysically),  and  phenomena,  or  things  as  they  appear 
(which  are  to  be  investigated  physically) ;  he  then  (in  the  writings 
after  1760)  attained  to  the  insight  that  a  metaphysics  in  the  sense 
of  rationalism  is  impossible,  that  philosophy  and  mathematics  must 
have  diametrically  opposed  methods,  and  that  philosophy  as  the 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  247 

empirical  knowledge  of  the  given  cannot  step  beyond  the  circle  of 
experience.  But  while  he  allowed  himself  to  be  comforted  by 
Voltaire  and  Rousseau  for  this  falling  away  of  metaphysical  in 
sight,  through  the  instrumentality  of  the  "natural  feeling"  for  the 
right  and  holy,  he  was  still  working  with  Lambert  at  an  improve 
ment  of  the  method  of  metaphysics,  and  when  he  found  this,  as  he 
hoped,  by  the  aid  of  Leibniz's  Nouveaux  Essais,  he  constructed 
in  bold  lines  the  mystico-dogmatic  system  of  his  Inaugural  Dis 
sertation. 

The  progress  from  this  point  to  the  System  of  Criticism  is 
obscure  and  controverted.  For  this  development,  and  for  the  time 
in  which  he  was  influenced  by  Hume,  as  well  as  for  the  direction 
which  that  influence  took,  consult  the  following  works  :  Fr.  Michelis, 
Kant  vor  und  nach  1770  (Braunsberg,  1871)  ;  Fr.  Paulsen,  Ver- 
such  einer  Entivicklungsgeschichte  der  Kantischen  Erkennt- 
nisstheorie  (Leipsic,  1875);  A.  Riehl,  Geschichte  und  Methode  dts 
philosophischen  Kriticismus  (Leips.  1876)  ;  B.  Erdmann,  Kant's 
Kriticismus  (Leips.  1878) ;  W.  Windelband,  Die  verschiedenen 
Phasen  der  Kantischen  I^ehre  ^'om  Ding-an-sich  {Vierteljahrs- 
schrift  filr  zvissenschaftliche  Philosophie,  1876).  Cf.  also  the 
writings  by  K.  Dieterich  on  Kant's  relation  to  Newton  and  Rous 
seau  under  the  title  Die  Kantische  Philosophic  in  ihrer  inneren 
Entzuicklungsgeschichte,  Freiburg  i.  B.  1885  ;  also  A.  Wreschner, 
Ernst  Plainer  und  Kant's  Kritik  der  reinen  Vernunft  (Leipsic, 
1893);  E.  Adickes,  Kant-Studien  (Kiel  and  Leipsic,  1895);  F. 
Paulsen,  Immanuel  Kant  (Stuttgart,  1898).  For  Kant  on  Evolu 
tion,  see  P.  Carus,  Kant  and  Spencer  (Chicago,  1900). 

From  the  adjustment  of  the  various  tendencies  of  Kant's 
thought  proceeded  the  "Doomsday-book"  of  German  philosophy, 
the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  (Riga,  1781).  It  received  a  series  of 
changes  in  the  second  edition  (1787),  and  these  became  the  objec, 
of  very  vigorous  controversies  after  attention  had  been  called  to 
them  by  Schelling  (W.,  V.  196)  and  Jacobi  (W.,  II.  291).  Cf.  con 
cerning  this,  the  writings  cited  above.  H.  Vaihinger,  Commentar 
zu  Kant's  Kritik  der  reinen  Vernunft  (Vol.  I.,  Stuttgart,  1887, 
Vol.  II.,  1892),  has  diligently  collected  the  literature.  Separate 
editions  of  the  Kritik,  by  K.  Kehrbach,  upon  the  basis  of  the  first 
edition,  and  by  B.  Erdmann  and  E.  Adickes  upon  the  basis  of  the 
second  edition,  have  been  published. 

There  is  an  English  translation  of  the  Critique  (2d  ed.),  by 
in  the  Bohn  Library,  and  also  one  by  Max  Miiller 


248  KANT'S  LIFE  AXD  PHILOSOPHY. 

(text  of  ist  ed.  with  supplements  giving  changes  of  2d  ed.),  Lond. 
1881.  We  have  further  a  Paraphrase  and  Commentary  by  Mahaffy 
and  Bernard,  2d  ed.,  Lond.  and  N.  Y.  1889;  and  partial  transla 
tions  in  J.  H.  Stirling's  Text-book  to  Kant,  and  in  Watson's  Selec 
tions,  Lond.  and  N.  Y.  1888.  This  last  contains  also  extracts  from 
the  ethical  writings  and  from  the  Critique  of  Judgment. 

The  additional  main  writings  of  Kant  in  his  critical  period  are  : 
Prolegomena  zu  einerjeden  kilnftigen  Metaphysik,  1783  ;  Grund- 
legung  zur  Metaphysik  der  Sitten,  1785  ;  Metaphysische  An- 

fangsgrunde  der  Naturzvissenschaft,  1785  ;  Kritik  der  prak- 
ti&chen  Vernunft,  1788;  Kritik  der  Urtheilskraft,  1790;  Die 
Religion  innerhalb  der  Grenzen  der  blossen  Vernunft,  1793 ; 
Zum  ewigen  Frieden,  1795 ;  Metaphysische  Anfangsgriinde 
der  Rechts-  und  Tugendlehre,  1797  ;  Der  Streit  der  Fakultdten, 
1798.  There  is  an  English  translation  of  the  Prolegomena,  by 
Mahaffy  and  Bernard,  Lond.  and  N.  Y.,  1889  ;  of  the  Prolegomena 
and  Metaphysical  Foundation  of  Natural  Science,  by  Bax,  Bohn 
Library  ;  of  the  ethical  writings,  including  the  first  part  of  the 
Religion  within  the  Bounds  of  Pure  Reason,  by  T.  K.  Abbott, 
4th  ed.,  Lond.  1889;  of  the  Critique  of  Judgment,  by  J.  H. 
Bernard,  Lond.  and  N.  Y.  1892  ;  of  the  Philosophy  of  Law,  by  W. 
Hastie,  Edin.  1887  ;  Principles  of  Politics,  including  the  essay  on 
Perpetual  Peace,  by  W.  Hastie,  Edin.  1891  ;  of  Kant's  Inaugural 
Dissertation,  W.  J.  Eckoff,  (New  York,  1894).  The  contents  of 
Kant's  Essays  and  Treatises,  2  vols. ,  Lond.  1798,  is  given  in 
Ueberiveg,  II.  138  (Eng.  tr.). 

Complete  editions  of  his  works  have  been  prepared  by  K. 
Rosenkranz  and  F.  W.  Schubert  (12  vols.,  Leips.  1833  ff.) ;  by  G. 
Hartenstein  (10  vols.,  Leips.  1838  f. ;  more  recently  8  vols.,  Leips. 
1867  ff.);  and  by  J.  v.  Kirchmann  (in  the  Philos.  Biblioth.}.  They 
contain,  besides  his  smaller  articles,  etc.,  his  lectures  upon  logic, 
pedagogy,  etc.,  and  his  letters.  A  survey  of  all  that  has  been  writ 
ten  by  Kant  (including  also  the  manuscript  of  the  Transition 

from  Metaphysics  to  Physics,  which  is  without  value  for  the  inter 
pretation  of  his  critical  system)  is  found  in  Ueberweg-Heinze,  III, 
§  24  ;  there,  too,  the  voluminous  literature  is  cited  with  great  com 
pleteness.  Of  this  we  can  give  here  only  a  choice  of  the  best  and 
most  instructive  ;  a  survey  of  the  more  valuable  literature,  ar 
ranged  according  to  its  material,  is  offered  by  the  article  Kant,  by 
W.  Windelband  in  Ersch  und  Gruber's  Enc.  The  Journal  of 
Speculative  Philosophy  contains  numerous  articles  upon  Kant. 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  249 

We  may  mention  also  Adamson,  The  Philosophy  of  Kant,  Edin, 
1879 ;  art.  Kant,  in  Enc.  Brit. ,  by  the  same  author  ;  arts,  in  Mind, 
Vol.  VI.,  by  J.  Watson,  and  in  Philos.  Review,  1893,  by  J.  G. 
Schurmann. — E.  Adickes  has  published  an  exhaustive  bibliography 
of  the  German  literature  in  the  Philos.  Review ;  1893  ff. 


THE  CRITIQUE  OF  PRACTICAL  REASON. 
AND  THE  CRITIQUE  OF  JUDGMENT. 

(AFTER  WEBER. l) 

I.    THE    CRITIQUE    OF    PRACTICAL    REASON.2 

A  LTHOUGH  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  reduces  us  to  a 
XX.  scepticism  which  is  all  the  more  absolute  because  it  is  rea 
soned,  proved,  cientifically  established,  and  legitimised,  it  would  be 
a  grave  mistake  to  consider  the  sage  of  Koenigsberg  as  a  sceptic  in 
the  traditional  sense,  and  to  impute  to  him  a  weakness  for  the  mate 
rialism  of  his  age.  Scepticism  is  the  upshot  of  the  Critique  of  Pure 
Reason;  it  is  not,  however,  the  ultimatum  of  Kantianism.  To  assert 
the  contrary  is  completely  to  misunderstand  the  spirit  of  the 
philosophy  of  Kant  and  the  final  purpose  of  his  critique.  This  is 
by  no  means  hostile  to  the  moral  faith  and  its  transcendent  object, 
but  wholly  in  its  favor.  It  is,  undoubtedly,  not  Kant's  intention  to 
"humiliate  "  reason,  as  Tertullian  and  Pascal  had  desired  to  do, 
but  to  assign  to  it  its  proper  place  among  all  our  faculties,  its  true 
role  in  the  complicated  play  of  our  spiritual  life.  Now,  this  place 
is,  according  to  Kant,  a  subordinate  one ;  this  function  is  re 
gulative  and  modifying,  not  constitutive  and  creative.  The  WILL, 
and  not  reason,  forms  the  basis  of  our  faculties  and  of  things. 
that  is  the  leading  thought  of  Kantian  philosophy.  While  reason 
becomes  entangled  in  inevitable  antinomies  and  involves  us  in 
doubts,  the  will  is  the  ally  of  faith,  the  source,  and  therefore,  the 
natural  guardian  of  our  moral  and  religious  beliefs.  Observe  that 

1  From  Weber's  History  of  Philosophy.  Translated  by  Frank  Thilly.  New 
York:  Scribner's.  Price,  $2.50.  Weber's  book  is  one  of  the  clearest,  con- 
cisest,  and  most  readable  of  the  histories  of  philosophies. 

2H.  Cohen,  Kant's  Begrundung  der  Ethik,  Berlin,  1877;  E.  Zeller,  Ueber 
das  Kantische  Moralprincip,  Berlin,  1880;  J.  G.  Schurman,  Kantian  Ethics 
and  the  Ethics  of  Evolution,  London,  1881;  N.  Porter,  Kant's  Ethics,  Chicago, 
1886 ;  F.  W.  Forster,  Der  Entwickelungsgang  der  Kantischen  Ethik,  etc.,  Ber 
lin,  1894  ;  Piinjer,  Die  Religionslehre  Kant's,  Jena,  1874. 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  paiLUbOPHY.  251 

Kant  in  no  wise  denies  the  existence  of  the  thing-in-itself,  of  the 
soul,  and  of  God,  but  only  the  possibility  of  proving  the  reality  of 
these  Ideas,  by  means  of  reasoning.  True,  he  combats  spirit 
ualistic  dogmatism,  but  the  same  blow  that  brings  it  down  over 
throws  materialism  ;  and  though  he  attacks  theism,  he  likewise  de 
molishes  the  dogmatic  pretensions  of  the  atheists.  What  he  combats 
to  the  utmost  and  pitilessly  destroys  is  the  dogmatism  of  theoretical 
reason,  under  whatever  form  it  may  present  itself,  whether  as 
theism  or  atheism,  spiritualism  or  materialism  ;  is  its  assumption 
of  authority  in  the  system  of  our  faculties  ;  is  the  prejudice  which 
attributes  metaphysical  capacity  to  the  understanding,  isolated 
from  the  -will  and  depending  on  its  ozvn  resources.  By  way  of 
retaliation—  and  here  he  reveals  the  depth  of  his  philosophic  faith 
—  he  concedes  a  certain  metaphysical  capacity  to  practical  reason, 
i.  c.,  to  ivill. 

Like  the  understanding,  the  will  has  its  own  character,  its 
original  forms,  its  particular  legislation,  a  legislation  which  Kant 
calls  "practical  reason."  In  this  new  domain,  the  problems  raised 
by  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  change  in  aspect  ;  doubts  are  dis 
sipated,  and  uncertainties  give  way  to  practical  certainty.  The 
moral  law  differs  essentially  from  physical  law,  as  conceived  by 
theoretical  reason.  Physical  law  is  irresistible  and  inexorable  ; 
the  moral  law  does  not  compel,  but  bind  ;  hence  it  implies  free 
dom.  Though  freedom  cannot  be  proved  theoretically,  it  is  not  in 
the  least  doubtful  to  the  will  :  it  is  a  postulate  of  practical  reason, 
an  immediate  fact  of  the  moral  consciousness.1 

Here  arises  one  of  the  great  difficulties  with  which  philosophy 
is  confronted  :  How  can  we  reconcile  the  postulate  of  practical  rea 
son  with  the  axiom  of  pure  reason  that  every  occurrence  in  the 
phenomenal  order  is  a  necessary  effect,  that  the  phenomenal  world 
is  governed  by  an  absolute  determinism  ?  Kant,  whose  belief  in 
free-will  is  no  less  ardent  than  his  love  of  truth,  cannot  admit  an 
absolute  incompatibility  between  natural  necessity  and  moral 
liberty.  The  conflict  of  reason  and  conscience,  regarding  freedom, 
can  only  be  a  seeming  one  ;  it  must  be  possible  to  resolve  the  an 
tinomy  without  violating  the  rights  of  the  intelligence  or  those  of 
the  will. 

The  solution  would,  undoubtedly,  be  impossible,  if  the  Cri 
tique  of  Pure  Reason  absolutely  denied  liberty,  but  the  fact  is,  it 


zur  Metaphysik  der  Sitten,  p.  80  (Rosenkranz)  ;  Kritik  der 
praktischen  I'ernunft,  p.  274. 


252  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

excludes  freedom  from  the  phenomenal  sphere  only,  and  not  from 
the  intelligible  and  transcendent  world,  which  exists  behind  the 
phenomenon,  though  it  is  unknowable.  Theoretical  reason  de 
clares  :  Freedom,  though  impossible  in  the  phenomenal  world,  is 
possible  in  the  absolute  order  ;  it  is  conceived  as  a  noumenon  ;  it 
is  intelligible  ;  and  practical  reason  adds  :  it  is  certain.  Hence, 
there  is  no  real  contradiction  between  the  faculty  of  knowledge 
and  of  will.  Our  acts  are  determined,  in  so  far  as  they  occur  in 
time  and  in  space,  indetermined  and  free,  in  so  far  as  the  source 
whence  they  spring,  our  intelligible  character,  is  independent  of 
these  two  forms  of  sensibility.1 

This  would  not  be  a  solution  if  time  and  space  were  objective 
realities,  as  dogmatic  philosophy  conceives  them.  From  that 
point  of  vieru,  Spinoza  is  right  in  denying  freedom.  However,  as 
soon  as  we  agree  with  criticism,  that  space  and,  above  all,  time  are 
modes  of  seeing  things,  and  do  not  affect  the  things  themselves, 
determinism  is  reduced  to  a  mere  theory  or  general  conception  of 
things,  a  theory  or  conception  which  reason  cannot  repudiate  with 
out  abdicating,  but  which  by  no  means  expresses  their  real  es 
sence. 

The  Kantian  solution  of  the  problem  of  freedom  at  first  sight 
provokes  a  very  serious  objection.  If  the  soul,  as  intelligible 
character,  does  not  exist  in  time,  if  it  is  not  a  phenomenon,  we 
can  no  longer  subsume  it  under  the  category  of  causality,  since  the 
categories  apply  only  to  phenomena  and  not  to  "  noumena.' 
Hence  it  ceases  to  be  a  cause  and  a  free  cause.  Nor  can  we  apply 
to  it  the  category  of  unity.  Hence  it  ceases  to  be  an  individual 
apart  from  other  individuals  :  it  is  identified  with  the  universal, 
the  eternal,  and  the  infinite.  Fichte,  therefore,  consistently  de 
duces  his  doctrine  of  the  absolute  ego  from  Kantian  premises. 
Our  philosopher,  however,  does  not  seem  to  have  the  slightest 
suspicion  that  this  is  the  logical  conclusion  of  this  theory.  Nay, 
he  postulates,  always  in  the  name  of  practical  reason,  individual 
immortality2  as  a  necessary  condition  of  the  solution  of  the  moral 
problem,  and  the  existence  of  a  God3  apart  from  the  intelligible 
ego,  as  the  highest  guarantee  of  the  moral  order  and  the  ultimate 
triumph  of  the  good.  It  is  true,  Kant's  theology  is  merely  an  ap 
pendix  to  his  ethics,  and  is  not  to  be  taken  very  seriously.  It  is 

\Kritik  der  praktischen  1'ernunft,  pp.  225  ff. 
J  Kritik  der  praktischen  Vcrnunft,  p.  261. 
3/</.,  p.  264. 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  253 

no  longer,  as  in  the  Middle  Ages,  the  queen  of  the  sciences,  but 
the  humble  servant  of  independent  ethics.  This  personal  God, 
afterwards  postulated  by  the  Critique  of  Practical  Reason,  forcibly 
reminds  us  of  the  celebrated  epigram  of  a  contemporary  of  our 
philosopher:  "If  there  were  no  God,  we  should  have  to  invent 
one." 

The  real  God  of  Kant  is  Freedom  in  the  service  of  the  ideal, 
or  the  good  Will  (der  gute  Witte)  1 

His  conviction  in  this  matter  is  most  clearly  expressed  by 
the  doctrine  of  the  primacy  of  practical  reason*  i.  e.,  of  the 
zvi'Il.3  Theoretical  reason  and  practical  reason,  though  not  directly 
contradicting  each  other,  are  slightly  at  variance  as  the  most  im 
portant  questions  of  ethics  and  religion,  the  former  tending  to  con 
ceive  liberty,  God,  and  the  absolute  as  ideals  having  no  demon 
strable  objective  existence,  the  latter  affirming  the  reality  of  the 
autonomous  soul,  responsibility,  immortality,  and  the  Supreme 
Being.  The  consequences  of  this  dualism  would  be  disastrous  if 
theoretical  reason  and  practical  reason  were  of  equal  rank ;  and 
they  would  be  still  more  disastrous,  were  the  latter  subordinated 
to  the  former.  But  the  authority  of  practical  reason  is  superior  to 
that  of  theoretical  reason,  and  in  real  life  the  former  predominates. 
Hence  we  should,  in  any  case,  act  as  if  it  zvere  proved  that  we 
are  free,  that  the  soul  is  immortal,  that  there  is  a  supreme  judge 
and  rewarder. 

In  certain  respects,  the  dualism  of  understanding  and  will  is  a 
happy  circumstance.  If  the  realities  of  religion,  God,  freedom, 
and  the  immortality  of  the  soul,  were  self-evident  truths,  or 
capable  of  theoretical  proof,  we  should  do  the  good  for  the  sake  of 
future  reward,  our  will  would  cease  to  be  autonomous,  our  acts 
would  no  longer  be  strictly  moral  ;  for  every  other  motive  except 
the  categorical  imperative  of  conscience  and  the  respect  which  it 
inspires,  be  it  friendship  or  even  the  love  of  God,  renders  the  will 
heteronomous,  and  deprives  its  acts  of  their  ethical  character. 
Moreover,  religion  is  true  only  when  completely  identical  with 
morality.  Religion  within  the  bounds  of  reason  consists  in  morality, 
nothing  more  nor  less.  The  essence  of  Christianity  is  eternal 

\Grundlegung  xur  Mctaphytik  der  Sitten,  p.  n  :  Es  ist  uberall  nichts  in 
der  Welt  J  a  uberhaupt  auch  ausser  derselben  zu  denkcn  moglich,  -was  ohne  Ein- 
ichrankung/ur  gut  konnte  gehalten  werden,  als  allein  ein  GUTER  WiLLE. 

IKritik  der  praktischen  Vernunft,?.  258. 

3 Id.,  pp.  105  ff. 


254  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

morality  ;  the  goal  of  the  church  is  the  triumph  of  right  in  human 
ity.  When  the  church  aims  at  a  different  goal,  it  loses  its  raison 
d'etre.1 

II.    CRITIQUE    OF   JUDGMENT.2 

While  the  Critique  of  Practical  Reason,  vrith  its  categorical 
imperative,  its  primacy  of  the  conscience,  and  its  absolute  inde 
pendence  of  morality,  satisfies  Kant's  moral  feeling  and  his  great 
love  of  liberty,  which  had  been  shaken  by  the  conclusions  of  the 
Critique  of  Pure  Reason ,  the  philosophical  instinct  reasserts  it 
self  in  his  aesthetics  and  teleology,  which  form  the  subject-matter 
of  his  Critique  of  Judgment.  We  have  seen  how,  in  the  Critique 
of  Pure  Reason,  he  universally  combines  synthesis  with  analysis, 
how  he  solders  together  the  heterogeneous  parts  of  the  cognitive 
apparatus  :  between  the  functions  of  sensibility  and  those  of  reason 
he  discovers  the  intermediate  function  of  the  idea  of  time,  which 
is  half  intuition,  half  category  ;  between  a  priori  concepts  which 
are  diametrically  opposed,  he  inserts  intermediary  categories.  The 
same  synthetic  impulse  leads  him,  in  his  Critique  of  Judgment, 
to  bridge  over  the  chasm  which  separates  theoretical  reason  and 
the  conscience.3 

The  aesthetical  and  teleological  sense  is  an  intermediate  faculty, 
a  connecting  link  between  the  understanding  and  the  will.  Truth 
is  the  object  of  the  understanding,  nature  and  natural  necessity  its 
subject-matter.  The  will  strives  for  the  good  ;  it  deals  with  free 
dom.  The  aesthetical  and  teleological  sense  (or  judgment  in  the 
narrow  sense  of  the  term)  is  concerned  with  what  lies  between  the 
true  and  the  good,  between  nature  and  liberty  :  we  mean  the 

1  Die  Religion  innerhalb  der  Grenzen  der  blossen  Vernunft,  pp.  130  ff. ;  205 
ff.— The  independent  morality  of  the  socialist  P.  J.  Proudhon  (1809—1865)  is 
grounded  on  these  principles.  It  is  based  on  the  following  proposition: 
"  Morality  must  cease  to  lean  on  theology  for  support,  it  must  free  itself  from 
all  so-called  revealed  dogmas,  and  base  itself  solely  on  conscience  and  the 
innate  principle  of  justice,  without  requiring  the  support  of  the  belief  in  God 
and  the  immortality  of  the  soul."  This  doctrine  of  Proudhon  has  been  re 
produced  and  popularized  by  a  weekly  journal,  the  "Morale  independante,' 
edited  by  Massol,  Morin  and  Coignet  (1895  ff-)- 

2[A.  Stadler,  Kant's  Teleologie,  etc.,  Berlin,  1874;  H.  Cohen,  Kant's  Be- 
gr  tin  dung  der  Aesthetik,  Berlin,  1889;  J.  Goldfriedrich,  Kant's  Aesthetik, 
Leipsic,  1895;  J.  H.  Tufts,  The  Sources  and  Development  of  Kant's  Teleology , 
Chicago,  1892.] 

ZXritik  der  Urtheilskraft ,  p.  14. 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  255 

beautiful  and  the  purposive.  Kant  calls  it  judgment  because  of 
the  analogy  between  its  manifestations  and  what  is  called  judg 
ment  in  logic,  like  the  judgment,  the  sense  of  the  beautiful  and  the 
teleological  establishes  a  relation  between  two  things  which  as 
such  have  nothing  in  common  :  between  what  ought  to  be  and  what 
is,  between  freedom  and  natural  necessity. 

i.  ^Esthetics. — The  sesthetical  sense  differs  both  from  the 
understanding  and  the  will.  It  is  neither  theoretical  nor  practical 
in  character;  it  is  a  phenomenon  sui generis.  But  it  has  this  in 
common  with  reason  and  will,  that  it  rests  on  an  essentially  sub 
jective  basis.  Just  as  reason  constitutes  the  true,  and  will  the 
good,  so  the  aesthetical  sense  makes  the  beautiful.  Beauty  does 
not  inhere  in  objects ;  it  does  not  exist  apart  from  the  assthetical 
sense;  it  is  the  product  of  this  sense,  as  time  and  space  are  the 
products  of  the  theoretical  sense.  That  is  beautiful  which  pleases 
(quality),  which  pleases  all  (quantity),  which  pleases  without  in 
terest  and  without  a  concept  (relation),  and  pleases  necessarily 
(modality).1 

What  characterizes  the  beautiful  and  distinguishes  it  from  the 
sublime,  is  the  feeling  of  peace,  tranquillity,  or  harmony  which  it 
arouses  in  us,  in  consequence  of  the  perfect  agreement  between 
the  understanding  and  the  imagination.  The  sublime,  on  the  other 
hand,  disturbs  us,  agitates  us,  transports  us.  Beauty  dwells  in  the 
form  ;  the  sublime,  in  the  disproportion  between  the  form  and  the 
content.  The  beautiful  calms  and  pacifies  us  ;  the  sublime  brings 
disorder  into  our  faculties ;  it  produces  discord  between  the  rea 
son,  which  conceives  the  infinite,  and  the  imagination,  which  has 
its  fixed  limits.  The  emotion  caused  in  us  by  the  starry  heavens, 
the  storm,  and  the  raging  sea  springs  from  the  conflict  aroused  by 
these  different  phenomena  between  our  reason,  which  can  measure 
the  forces  of  nature  and  the  heavenly  distances  without  being  over 
whelmed  by  the  enormous  figures,  and  our  imagination,  which 
cannot  follow  reason  into  the  depths  of  infinity.  Man  has  a  feel 
ing  of  grandeur,  because  he  himself  is  grand  through  reason.  The 
animal  remains  passive  in  the  presence  of  the  grand  spectacles  of 
nature,  because  its  intelligence  does  not  rise  beyond  the  level  of  its 
imagination.  Hence  we  aptly  say,  the  sublime  elevates  the  soul 
(das  Erhabene  ist  erhebend).  In  the  feeling  of  the  sublime,  man 
reveals  himself  as  a  being  infinite  in  reason,  finite  in  imagi- 

1  Kritik  der  Urtheilskraft ',  pp.  45  ff. 


256  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

nation.  Both  infinite  and  finite  :  how  is  that  possible  ?  Kant  can 
not  fathom  this  mystery  without  surpassing  the  limits  which  he  has 
prescribed  to  knowledge.1 

2.  Teleology? — There  are  two  kinds  of  purposiveness.  The 
one  arouses  in  us,  immediately  and  without  the  aid  of  any  con 
cept,  a  feeling  of  pleasure,  satisfaction,  and  inner  harmony  :  this  is 
subjective  finality,  which  constitutes  the  beautiful.  The  other  also 
arouses  pleasure,  but  mediately,  in  consequence  of  an  experience 
or  an  intermediate  process  of  reasoning  :  this  is  objective  finality, 
which  constitutes  the  suitable  (das  Zweckmcissige}.  Thus,  a 
flower  may  be  both  the  object  of  an  aesthetical  judgment  in  the 
artist,  and  of  a  ideological  judgment  in  the  naturalist,  who  has 
tested  its  value  as  a  remedy.  Only,  the  judgment  which  stamps  it 
as  beautiful  is  immediate  and  spontaneous,  while  that  of  the 
naturalist  depends  on  previous  experience. 

The  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  regards  every  phenomenon  as  a 
necessary  effect,  and  therefore  excludes  purposiveness  from  the 
phenomenal  world.  Physics  merely  enumerates  an  infinite  series 
of  causes  and  effects.  Teleology  introduces  between  the  cause  and 
the  effect,  considered  as  the  end  or  goal,  the  means,  the  in 
strumental  cause.  Theoretically,  teleology  is  valueless.  However, 
we  cannot  avoid  it  so  long  as  we  apply  our  teleological  sense  to 
the  study  of  nature.  Unless  we  abandon  one  of  our  faculties, 
which  is  as  real  and  inevitable  as  reason  and  will,  we  cannot  help 
recognizing  purposiveness  in  the  structure  of  the  eye,  the  ear,  and 
the  organism  in  general.  Though  mechanism  fully  explains  the 
inorganic  world,  the  teleological  view  forces  itself  upon  us  when 
we  come  to  consider  anatomy,  physiology,  and  biology. 

The  antinomy  of  mechanism,  affirmed  by  the  theoretical  rea 
son,  and  teleology,  claimed  by  the  teleological  sense,  is  no  more 
insoluble  than  that  of  necessity  and  freedom.3  Teleology  is  noth 
ing  but  a  theory  concerning  phenomena.  It  no  more  expresses  the 
essence  of  things  than  mechanism.  This  essence  is  as  unknowable 
for  the  Critique  of  Judgment  as  for  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason. 
Things-in-themselves  are  not  in  time  ;  they  have  no  succession,  no 
duration.  According  to  mechanism,  the  cause  and  its  effect,  ac 
cording  to  teleology,  the  free  cause,  the  means,  and  the  goal  at 
which  it  aims,  follow  each  other,  i.  e. ,  they  are  separated  in  time. 

1  Kritik  der  Urthezlskraft,  pp.  97  ff. ;  399  ft. 
2/</  ,  pp.  239  ff.  §  Kritik  der  Vrtheilskraft,  pp.  302  ff. 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  257 

But  time  is  merely  an  a  priori form  of  intuition,  a  mode  of  con 
ceiving  things ;  as  such  and  apart  from  my  thought  or  my  theory, 
the  cause  and  the  effect  of  the  mechanist,  the  creative  agent,  the 
means,  and  the  goal  of  the  teleologist,  are  in  each  other,  insepar 
able,  simultaneous.  Imagine  an  understanding  which  is  not  bound 
to  the  a  priori  forms  of  space  and  time  like  ours,  a  free  and  ab 
solute  intellectual  intuition  :  such  an  understanding  would  perceive 
the  cause,  the  means,  and  the  end  at  one  glance ;  it  would  identify 
the  end  and.  the  principle ;  the  end  would  not  follow  the  efficient 
cause,  but  would  be  immanent  in  it  and  identical  with  it.  Im 
manent  teleology,  which  identifies  the  ends  of  nature  with  the  act 
ing  causes,  is  the  natural  solution  of  the  antinomy  of  mechanism 
and  purposiveness. 

We  see  that  the  subjectivity  of  time  and  space  is  the  most 
original  and,  on  the  whole,  the  most  fruitful  of  Kant's  teachings. 
There  is  no  question  so  subtle,  no  problem  so  obscure,  as  not  to 
be  illuminated  by  it.  Space  and  time  are  the  eyes  of  the  mind, 
the  organs  which  reveal  to  it  its  inexhaustible  content.  These 
organs  are  at  the  same  time  the  boundaries  of  its  knowledge.  But 
in  spite  of  this  insurmountable  barrier,  it  feels  free,  immortal,  and 
divine  ;  and  it  declares  its  independence  in  the  field  of  action.  It 
is  the  mind  which  prescribes  its  laws  to  the  phenomenal  world  ;  it 
is  the  mind  from  which  the  moral  law  proceeds  ;  it  is  the  mind  and 
its  judgment  which  make  the  beautiful  beautiful.  In  short,  the 
three  Critiques  culminate  in  absolute  spiritualism.  Kant  compared 
his  work  to  that  of  Copernicus  :  just  as  the  author  of  the  Celestial 
Revolutions  puts  the  sun  in  the  place  of  the  earth  in  our  planetary 
system,  so  the  author  of  the  Critique  places  the  mind  in  the  centre 
of  the  phenomenal  world  and  makes  the  latter  dependent  upon  it. 
Kant's  philosophy  is,  undoubtedly,  the  most  remarkable  and  most 
fruitful  product  of  modern  thought.  With  a  single  exception, 
perhaps,1  the  greatest  systems  which  our  century  has  produced  are 
continuations  of  Kantianism.  Even  those — and  their  number  has 
grown  during  the  last  thirty  years — who  have  again  taken  up  the 
Anglo  French  philosophy  of  the  eighteenth  century,  revere  the 
illustrious  name  of  Immanuel  Kant. 

IWe  mean  the  system  of  Comte,  which  is  closely  related  to  the  French 
philosophy  of  the  eighteenth  century.  Comte  himself  says,  in  a  letter  to 
Gustave  d'Eichlhal,  dated  December  loth,  1824  :  "  I  have  always  considered 
Kant  not  only  as  a  very  powerful  thinker,  but  also  as  the  metaphysician  who 
most  closely  approximates  the  positive  philosophy." 


KANT'S  VIEWS  ON  RELIGION. 

(AFTER  scHWBGLBR.1) 

RANT'S  views  of  religion  appear  in  his  treatise  on  Religion 
within  the  Bounds  of  Pure  Reason.  The  fundamental  idea 
of  this  treatise  is  the  reduction  of  religion  to  morality.  Between 
morality  and  religion  there  may  be  the  twofold  relation,  that  either 
morality  is  founded  upon  religion,  or  else  religion  upon  morality. 
If  the  first  relation  were  real,  it  would  give  us  fear  and  hope  as 
principles  of  moral  action  ;  but  this  cannot  be ;  there  remains, 
therefore,  only  the  second.  Morality  leads  necessarily  to  religion, 
because  the  highest  good  is  a  necessary  ideal  of  the  reason,  and 
this  can  only  be  realized  through  a  God  ;  but  in  no  way  may  reli 
gion  first  incite  us  to  virtue,  for  the  idea  of  God  may  never  become 
a  moral  motive.  Religion,  according  to  Kant,  is  the  recognition 
of  all  our  duties  as  divine  commands.  It  is  revealed  religion  when 
f  must  first  know  that  something  is  a  divine  command,  in  order  to 
know  that  it  is  my  duty :  it  is  natural  religion  when  I  must  first 
know  that  something  is  my  duty,  in  order  to  know  that  it  is  a  di 
vine  command.  The  Church  is  an  ethical  community,  which  has 
ior  its  end  the  fulfilment  and  the  most  perfect  exhibition  of  moral 
tommands, — a  union  of  those  who  with  united  energies  purpose  to 
resist  evil  and  advance  morality.  The  Church,  in  so  far  as  it  is  no 
Voject  of  a  possible  experience,  is  called  the  invisible  Church, 
which,  as  such,  is  merely  the  idea  of  the  union  of  all  the  righteous 
under  the  divine  moral  government  of  the  world.  The  visible 
Church,  on  the  other  hand,  is  that  which  represents  the  kingdom 
of  God  upon  earth,  so  far  as  this  can  be  attained  through  men. 
The  requisites,  and  hence  also  the  characteristics  of  the  true  visi 
ble  Church  (which  are  divided  according  to  the  table  of  the  cate 
gories  since  this  Church  is  given  in  experience)  are  the  following: 

ISchwegler's  History  of  Philosophy.    Translated  by  Seelye.     New  York 
Appleton    Schwegler's  compendium  has  enjoyed  the  greatest  popularity  both 
in  Germany  and  abroad,  for  its  accuracy  and  trustworthiness. 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  259 

(a)  In  respect  of  quantity  the  Church  must  be  total  or  universal; 
and  though  it  may  be  divided  in  accidental  opinions,  yet  must  it  be 
instituted  upon  such  principles  as  will  necessarily  lead  to  a 
universal  union  in  one  single  church,  (b)  The  quality  of  the  true 
visible  Church  is  purity,  as  a  union  under  no  other  than  mor^l 
motives,  since  it  is  at  the  same  time  purified  from  the  stupidness 
i;£  superstition  and  the  madness  of  fanaticism,  (c)  The  relation 
of  the  members  of  the  Church  to  each  other  rests  upon  the  principle 
of  freedom.  The  Church  is,  therefore,  zfree  state,  neither  a  hie 
rarchy  nor  a  democracy,  but  a  voluntary,  universal,  and  enduring 
spiritual  union,  (d)  In  respect  of  modality  the  Church  demands 
that  its  constitution  should  be  unchangeable.  The  laws  them 
selves  may  not  change,  though  one  may  reserve  to  himself  the 
privilege  of  changing  some  accidental  arrangements  which  relate 
simply  to  the  administration  — That  alone  which  can  establish  a 
universal  Church  is  the  moral  faith  of  the  reason,  for  this  alone  can 
be  shared  by  the  convictions  of  every  man.  But,  because  of  the 
peculiar  weakness  of  human  nature,  we  can  never  reckon  enough 
on  this  pure  faith  to  build  a  Church  on  it  alone,  for  men  are  not 
easily  convinced  that  the  striving  after  virtue  and  an  irreproach 
able  life  is  every  thing  which  God  demands  :  they  always  suppose 
that  they  must  oft^r  to  God  a  special  service  prescribed  by  tradi 
tion,  which  only  amounts  to  this — that  he  is  served. 

To  establish  a  Charch,  we  must  therefore  have  a  statutory 
faith  historically  grouuded  npon  facts.  This  is  the  so-called 
faith  of  the  Church.  In  every  Church  there  are  therefore  two  ele 
ments — the  purely  moral,  or  the  faith  of  reason,  and  the  historico- 
statutory,  or  the  faith  of  the  Church  It  depends  now  upon  the  re 
lation  of  these  two  elements  whether  a  Church  shall  have  any 
worth  or  not.  The  statutory  element  should  ever  be  only  the 
vehicle  of  the  moral  element,  Just  so  soon  as  this  element  becomes 
in  itself  an  independent  end,  claiming  an  independent  validity,  will 
the  Church  become  corrupt  and  irrational,  and  whenever  the 
Church  passes  over  to  the  pure  faith  of  reason,  it  approximates  to 
the  kingdom  of  God.  Upon  this  principle  we  may  distinguish  the 
true  from  the  spurious  service  of  the  kingdom  of  God,  religion 
from  priestcraft.  A  dogma  has  worth  alone  in  so  far  as  it  has  a 
moral  content.  The  apostle  Paul  himself  would  scarcely  have 
given  credit  to  the  dicta-  of  the  creed  of  the  Church  without  this 
moral  faith.  From  the  doctrine  of  Trinity,  e.  g.t  taken  literally, 
nothing  actually  practical  can  be  derived.  Whether  we  have  to 


260  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

reverence  in  the  Godhead  three  persons  or  ten  makes  no  differ 
ence,  if  in  both  cases  we  have  the  same  rules  for  our  conduct  of 
life.  The  Bible  also,  with  its  interpretation,  must  be  considered 
in  a  moral  point  of  view.  The  records  of  revelation  must  be  inter 
preted  in  a  sense  which  will  harmonize  with  the  universal  rules  of 
the  religion  of  reason.  Reason  is  in  religious  things  the  highest 
fnterpreter  of  the  Bible.  This  interpretation  in  reference  to  some 
texts  may  seem  forced,  yet  it  must  be  preferred  to  any  such  literal 
interpretation  as  would  contain  nothing  for  morality,  or  perhaps 
go  against  every  moral  feeling.  That  such  a  moral  signification 
may  always  be  found  without  ever  entirely  repudiating  the  literal 
sense,  results  from  the  fact  that  the  foundation  for  an  ethical  reli 
gion  lay  originally  in  the  human  reason.  We  need  only  to  divest 
the  representations  of  the  Bible  of  their  mythical  dress  (an  attempt 
which  Kant  has  himself  made,  by  an  ethical  interpretation  of  some 
of  the  weightiest  doctrines),  in  order  to  attain  for  them  a  rational 
meaning  which  shall  be  universally  valid.  The  historical  element 
of  the  sacred  books  is  in  itself  of  no  account.  The  maturer  the 
reason  becomes,  the  more  it  can  hold  fast  for  itself  the  moral  sense, 
so  much  the  more  unnecessary  will  be  the  statutory  institutions  of 
the  faith  of  the  Church.  The  transition  from  the  creed  of  the 
Church  to  the  pure  faith  of  reason  is  the  approximation  to  the 
kingdom  of  God,  to  which  however,  we  can  only  approach  nearer 
and  nearer  in  an  infinite  progress.  The  actual  realization  of  the 
kingdom  of  God  is  the  end  of  the  world,  the  termination  of  history 


K/>NT  AND  MATERIALISM. 
(AFTER  LANGE.') 

AS  a  routed  army  looks  around  it  for  a  firm  point  where  it  may 
hope  to  collect  again  into  order,  so  recently  there  has  been 
heard  everywhere  in  philosophic  circles  the  cry,  "Retreat  tc 
Kant ! "  Only  more  recently,  however,  has  this  retreat  to  Kant 
become  a  reality,  and  it  is  found  that  at  bottom  the  standpoint  of 
the  great  Konigsberg  philosopher  could  never  have  been  properly 
described  as  obsolete ;  nay,  that  we  have  every  reason  to  plunge 
into  the  depths  of  the  Kantian  system  with  most  serious  efforts, 
such  as  have  hitherto  been  spent  upon  scarcely  any  other  philoso 
pher  save  Aristotle. 

Misapprehension  and  impetuous  productiveness  have  com 
bined  in  an  intellectually  active  age  to  break  through  the  strict 
barriers  which  Kant  had  imposed  upon  speculation.  The  reaction 
which  succeeded  the  metaphysical  intoxication  contributed  the 
more  to  the  return  to  the  prematurely  abandoned  position,  as  men 
sound  themselves  again  confronted  by  the  Materialism  which  at 
the  appearance  of  Kant  had  disappeared  and  left  scarcely  a  wrack 
behind.  At  present  we  have  not  only  a  young  school  of  Kantians 
in  the  narrower  and  wider  sense,  but  those  also  who  wish  to  try 
other  paths  see  themselves  compelled  first  to  reckon  with  Kant, 
and  to  offer  a  special  justification  for  departing  from  his  ways. 
Even  the  factitious  and  exaggerated  enthusiam  for  Schopenhauer's 
philosophy  partly  owed  its  origin  to  a  related  tendency,  whi,"e  in 
many  cases  it  formed  for  more  logical  minds  a  transition  to  Kant. 
But  a  special  emphasis  must  here  be  laid  on  the  friendly  attitude 
of  men  of  science,  who,  so  far  as  Materialism  failed  to  satisfy 
them,  have  inclined  for  ihe  most  part  to  a  way  of  thinking  which, 
in  very  essential  points,  agrees  with  that  of  Kant. 

\History  of  Materialism.     Trans,  by  Thomas.     3  vols.     London :  Triibnp 

~o.     1880. 


262  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

And  it  is,  in  fact,  by  no  means  strictly  orthodox  Kantianism 
upon  which  we  must  have  laid  distinctive  stress;  least  of  all  that 
dogmatic  turn  with  which  Schieiden  thought  he  could  crush  Mate 
rialism  when  he  compared  Kant,  Fries,  and  Apelt  with  Keppler; 
Newton,  and  Laplace,  and  maintained  that  by  their  labors  the 
ideas  "Soul,"  "Freedom,"  "God,"  were  as  firmly  established  as 
the  laws  of  the  stellar  world.  Such  dogmatism  is  entirely  foreign 
to  the  spirit  of  the  critique  of  reason,  although  Kant  personally 
attached  great  value  to  his  having  withdrawn  these  very  ideas 
from  the  controversy  of  the  schools,  by  relegating  them,  as  utterly 
incapable  as  well  of  positive  as  negative  proof,  to  the  sphere  of 
practical  philosophy.  But  the  whole  of  the  practical  philosophy 
is  the  variable  and  perishable  part  of  Kant's  philosophy,  powerful 
as  were  its  effects  upon  his  contemporaries.  Only  its  site  is  im 
perishable,  not  the  edifice  that  the  master  has  erected  on  this  site. 
Even  the  demonstration  of  this  site,  as  of  a  free  ground  for  the 
building  of  ethical  systems,  can  scarcely  be  numbered  among  the 
permanent  elements  of  the  system,  and  therefore,  if  we  are  speak 
ing  of  the  salvation  of  moral  ideas,  nothing  is  more  unsuitable 
than  to  compare  Kant  with  Keppler,  to  say  nothing  of  Newton  and 
Laplace.  Much  rather  must  we  seek  for  the  whole  importance  of 
the  great  reform  which  Kant  inaugurated  in  his  criticism  of  the 
theoretical  reason;  here  lies,  in  fact,  even  for  ethics,  the  lasting 
importance  of  the  critical  philosophy,  which  not  only  aided  the 
development  of  a  particular  system  of  ethical  ideas,  but,  if  prop 
erly  carried  on,  is  capable  of  affording  similar  aid  to  the  changing 
requirements  of  various  epochs  of  culture. 

Kant  himself  was  very  far  from  comparing  himself  with  Kep 
pler;  but  he  made  another  comparison,  that  is  more  significant 
and  appropriate.  He  compared  his  achievement  to  that  of  Coper 
nicus.  But  this  achievement  consisted  in  this,  that  he  reversed 
the  previous  standpoint  of  metaphysics.  Copernicus  dared,  "by 
a  paradoxical  yet  true  method,"  to  seek  the  observed  motions,  no, 
in  the  heavenly  bodies,  but  in  their  observers.  Not  less  "para 
doxical"  must  it  appear  to  the  sluggish  mind  of  man  when  Kant 
lightly  and  certainly  overturns  our  collective  experience,  with  all 
the  historical  and  exact  sciences,  by  the  simple  assumption  that 
our  notions  do  not  regulate  themselves  according  to  things,  but 
things  according  to  our  notions.1  It  follows  immediately  from 

1  Compare  the  preface  to  the  second  edition  of  the  Critique.   Kant  indeed 
lets  it  here  appear  (note  to  p.  xxii.,  Hartenst.,  iii.  ao  ff.)  that  in  thoroughgoing 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  263 

cnis  that  the  objects  of  experience  altogether  are  only  our  objects; 
that  the  whole  objective  world  is,  in  a  word,  not  absolute  objectiv 
ity,  but  only  objectivity  for  man  and  any  similarly  organised  be 
ings,  while  behind  the  phenomenal  world,  the  absolute  nature  of 
things,  the  "  thing-in-itself  "  is  veiled  in  impenetrable  darkness. 

criticism  he  claims  the  rOle  of  a  Newton,  by  whose  theory  had  been  prtrvta 
what  Copernicus  in  his  opinion  (comp.  as  to  this  vol.  I.,  p.  230)  had  only  pro 
posed  as  "hypothesis."  But  for  the  purpose  of  gaining  a  first  view  of  the 
nature  of  the  Kantian  reform,  the  comparison  with  Copernicus  made  in  the 
preface  is  more  important 


KANT  AND  DEISM. 

(AFTER  HEINRICH  HEINE.1) 

LESSING  died  at  Brunswick  in  1781,  misunderstood,  hated, 
and  decried.  In  the  same  year  appeared  at  Konigsberg  Im- 
manuel  Kant's  Critique  of  Pure  Reason.  With  this  book 
(which  through  a  singular  delay  did  not  become  generally  known 
till  the  close  of  the  decade)  there  begins  in  Germany  an  intellectual 
revolution  which  offers  the  most  striking  analogies  to  the  material 
revolution  in  France,  and  which  must  to  the  deeper  thinkers  ap 
pear  of  at  least  as  great  importance  as  the  latter.  It  developed  it 
self  in  the  same  phases,  and  between  both  revolutions  there  exists 
the  most  remarkable  parallelism.  On  each  side  of  the  Rhine  we 
see  the  same  breach  with  the  past ;  all  respect  for  tradition  is  with 
drawn.  As  here,  in  France,  every  privilege,  so  there,  in  Germany, 
every  thought,  must  justify  itself  ;  as  here,  the  monarchy,  the  key 
stone  of  the  old  social  edifice,  so  there,  deism,  the  keystone  of  the 
old  intellectual  regime,  falls  from  its  place. 

Of  this  catastrophe,  the  2ist  of  January,  for  deism,  we  shall 
speak  in  the  concluding  part  of  this  volume.  A  peculiar  awe,  a 
mysterious  piety,  overcomes  us.  Our  heart  is  full  of  shuddering 
compassion  :  it  is  the  old  Jehovah  himself  that  is  preparing  for 
death.  We  have  known  him  so  well  from  his  cradle  in  Egypt, 
where  he  was  reared  among  the  divine  calves  and  crocodiles,  the 
sacred  onions,  ibises,  and  cats.  We  have  seen  him  bid  farewell  to 
these  companions  of  his  childhood  and  to  the  obelisks  and  sphinxes 
of  his  native  Nile,  to  become  in  Palestine  a  little  god-king  amidst 
a  poor  shepherd  people,  and  to  inhabit  a  temple-palace  of  his  own. 
We  have  seen  him  later  coming  into  contact  with  Assyrian-Baby 
lonian  civilisation,  renouncing  his  all-too-human  passions,  no 

From  Religion  and  Philosophy  in  Germany.  Translated  by  John  Snod- 
grass.  Boston  :  Houghton,  Mifflin  &  Co.,  1882.  This  work  by  Heine  is  cele 
brated  for  its  trenchant  wit,  and  is  the  literary  story  of  German  philosophy 
par  excellence. 


titt 


bee 


reitten 


t>  o  n 


Emmanuel    $  a  R  t 


i  g  o, 

grtet>ricf) 
1781. 


266  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

longer  giving  vent  to  fierce  wrath  and  vengeance,  at  least  no 
longer  thundering  at  every  trifle.  We  have  seen  him  migrate  to 
Rome,  the  capital,  where  he  abjures  all  national  prejudices  and 
proclaims  the  celestial  equality  of  all  nations,  and  with  such  fine 
phrases  establishes  an  opposition  to  the  old  Jupiter,  and  intrigues 
ceaselessly  till  he  attains  supreme  authority,  and  from  the  Capitoi 
rules  the  city  and  the  world,  urbem  et  orbem.  We  have  seen  how, 
growing  still  more  spiritualised,  he  becomes  a  loving  father,  a 
universal  friend  of  man,  a  benefactor  of  the  world,  a  philanthro 
pist  ;  but  all  this  could  avail  him  nothing  ! 

Hear  ye  not  the  bells  resounding?  Kneel  down.  They  are 
bringing  the  sacraments  to  a  dying  god  ! 

*         *         * 

It  is  related  that  an  English  mechanician,  who  had  already  in 
vented  the  most  ingenious  machines,  at  last  took  it  into  his  head 
to  construct  a  man  ;  and  that  he  succeeded.  The  work  of  his 
hands  deported  itself  and  acted  quite  like  a  human  being  ;  it  even 
contained  within  its  leathern  breast  a  sort  of  apparatus  of  human 
sentiment,  differing  not  greatly  from  the  habitual  sentiments  of 
Englishmen;  it  could  communicate  its  emotions  by  articulate 
sounds,  and  the  noise  of  wheels  in  its  interior,  of  springs  and  es 
capements,  which  was  distinctly  audible,  reproduced  the  genuine 
English  pronunciation.  This  automaton,  in  short,  was  an  accom 
plished  gentleman,  and  nothing  was  wanting  to  render  it  com 
pletely  human  except  a  soul.  But  the  English  mechanician  had 
not  the  power  to  bestow  on  hir  work  this  soul,  and  the  poor 
creature,  having  become  conscious  of  its  imperfection,  tormented 
its  creator  day  and  night  with  supplication  for  a  soul.  This  re 
quest,  daily  repeated  with  growing  urgency,  became  at  last  so  in 
supportable  to  the  poor  artist  that  he  took  to  flight  in  order  to  es 
cape  from  his  own  masterpiece.  But  the  automaton  also  took  the 
mail  coach,  pursued  him  over  the  whole  continent,  travelled  in 
cessantly  at  his  heels,  frequently  overtook  him,  and  then  gnashed 
and  growled  in  his  ears,  Give  me  a  soul!  These  two  figures  may 
now  be  met  with  in  every  country,  and  he  only  who  knows  their 
peculiar  relationship  to  each  other  can  comprehend  their  unwonted 
haste  and  their  haggard  anxiety.  But  as  soon  as  we  are  made 
aware  of  their  strange  relationship,  we  at  once  discover  in  them 
something  of  a  general  character  ;  we  see  how  one  portion  of  the 
English  people  is  becoming  weary  of  its  mechanical  existence,  and 
is  demanding  a  soul,  whilst  the  other  portion,  tormented  by  such  i 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  267 

request,  is  driven  about  in  all  directions,  and  that  neither  of  them 
can  endure  matters  at  home  any  longer. 

The  story  is  a  terrible  one.  It  is  a  fearful  thing  when  the 
bodies  we  have  created  demand  of  us  a  soul ;  but  it  is  a  far  more 
dreadful,  more  terrible,  more  awful  thing  when  we  have  created  a 
soul,  to  hear  that  soul  demanding  of  us  a  body,  and  to  behold  it 
pursuing  us  with  this  demand.  The  thought  to  which  we  have 
given  birth  is  such  a  soul,  and  it  leaves  us  no  rest  until  we  have 
endowed  it  with  a  body,  until  we  have  given  it  sensible  reality. 
Thought  strives  to  become  action,  the  word  to  become  flesh,  and, 
marvellous  to  relate,  man,  like  God  in  the  Bible,  needs  only  to  ex 
press  his  thought  and  the  world  takes  form  ;  there  is  light  or  dark 
ness  ;  the  waters  separate  themselves  from  the  dry  land  ;  or  it  may 
even  be  that  wild  beasts  are  brought  forth.  The  world  is  the  sign- 
manual  of  the  word. 

Mark  this,  ye  proud  men  of  action  ;  ye  are  nothing  but  un 
conscious  hodmen  of  the  men  of  thought  who,  often  in  humblest 
stillness,  have  appointed  you  your  inevitable  task.  Maximilian 
Robespierre  was  merely  the  hand  of  Jean  Jacques  Rousseau,  the 
bloody  hand  that  drew  from  the  womb  of  time  the  body  whose  soul 
Rousseau  had  created.  May  not  the  restless  anxiety  that  troubled 
the  life  of  Jean  Jacques  have  caused  such  stirrings  within  him 
that  he  already  foreboded  the  kind  of  accoucheur  that  was  needed 
to  bring  his  thought  living  into  the  world  ? 

Old  Fontenelle  may  have  been  right  when  he  said  :  "If  I  held 
all  the  truths  of  the  universe  in  my  hand,  I  would  be  very  careful 
not  to  open  it."  I,  for  my  part,  think  otherwise.  If  I  held  all  the 
truths  of  the  world  in  my  hand,  I  might  perhaps  beseech  you  in 
stantly  to  cut  off  that  hand  ;  but,  in  any  case,  I  should  not  long 
hold  it  closed.  I  was  not  born  to  be  a  gaoler  of  thoughts  ;  by 
Heaven  !  I  would  set  them  free.  What  though  they  were  to  in 
carnate  themselves  in  the  most  hazardous  realities,  what  though 
they  were  to  range  through  all  lands  like  a  mad  bacchanalian  pro 
cession,  what  though  they  were  to  crush  with  their  thyrsus  our 
most  innocent  flowers,  what  though  they  were  to  invade  our  hos 
pitals  and  chase  from  his  bed  the  old  sick  world — my  heart  would 
bleed,  no  doubt,  and  I  myself  would  suffer  thereby  !  For  alas  !  I 
too  am  part  of  this  old  sick  world,  and  the  poet  says  truly,  one  may 
mock  at  his  crutches  yet  not  be  able  to  walk  any  better  for  that.  I 
am  the  most  grievously  sick  of  you  all,  and  am  the  more  to  be 
pitied  since  I  know  what  health  is ;  but  you  do  not  know  it,  you 


268  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

whom  I  envy  ;  you  are  capable  of  dying  without  perceiving  your 
dying  condition.  Yea,  many  of  you  are  already  long  since  dead, 
though  maintaining  that  your  real  life  is  just  beginning.  When  I 
try  to  dispel  such  a  delusion,  then  you  are  angry  with  me  and  rail 
at  me,  and,  more  horrible  still,  the  dead  rush  upon  and  mock  at 
me,  and  more  loathsome  to  me  than  their  insults  is  the  smell  of 
their  putrefaction.  Hence,  ye  spectres  !  I  am  about  to  speak  of  a 
man  whose  mere  name  has  the  might  of  an  exorcism ;  I  speak  of 
Immanuel  Kant. 

It  is  said  that  night-wandering  spirits  are  filled  with  terror  at 
sight  of  the  headsman's  axe.  With  what  mighty  fear,  then,  must 
they  be  stricken  when  there  is  held  up  to  them  Kant's  Critique 
of  Pure  Reason  \  This  is  the  sword  that  slew  deism  in  Ger 
many. 

To  speak  frankly,  you  French  have  been  tame  and  moderate 
compared  with  us  Germans.  At  most,  you  could  but  kill  a  king, 
and  he  had  already  lost  his  head  before  you  guillotined  him.  For 
accompaniment  to  such  deed  you  must  needs  cause  such  a  drum 
ming  and  shrieking  and  stamping  of  feet  that  the  whole  universe 
trembled.  To  compare  Maximilian  Robespierre  with  Immanuel 
Kant  is  to  confer  too  high  an  honour  upon  the  former.  Maximil- 
lian  Robespierre,  the  great  citizen  of  the  Rue  Saint  Honore",  had, 
it  is  true,  his  sudden  attacks  of  destructiveness  when  it  was  a  ques 
tion  of  the  monarchy,  and  his  frame  was  violently  convulsed  when 
the  fit  of  regicidal  epilepsy  was  on  ;  but  as  soon  as  it  came  to  be  a 
question  about  the  Supreme  Being,  he  wiped  the  white  froth  from 
his  lips,  washed  the  blood  from  his  hands,  donned  his  blue  Sunday 
coat  with  silver  buttons,  and  stuck  a  nosegay  in  the  bosom  of  his 
broad  vest. 

The  history  of  Immanuel  Kant's  life  is  difficult  to  portray,  for 
he  had  neither  life  nor  history.  He  led  a  mechanical,  regular 
almost  abstract  bachelor  existence  in  a  little  retired  street  of  K6- 
nigsberg,  an  old  town  on  the  north  eastern  frontier  of  Germany. 
I  do  not  believe  that  the  great  clock  of  the  cathedral  performed  in 
a  more  passionless  and  methodical  manner  its  daily  routine  than 
did  its  townsman,  Immanuel  Kant.  Rising  in  the  morning,  coffee- 
drinking,  writing,  reading  lectures,  dining,  walking,  everything  had 
its  appointed  time,  and  the  neighbours  knew  that  it  was  exactly 
half-past  three  o'clock  when  Immanuel  Kant  stepped  forth  from 
his  house  in  his  grey,  tight-fitting  coat,  with  his  Spanish  cane  in 
his  hand,  and  betook  himself  to  the  little  linden  avenue  called  after 


KAN  I 'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  269 

him  to  this  day  the  "Philosopher's  Walk."  Summer  and  winter 
he  walked  up  and  down  it  eight  times,  and  when  the  weather  was 
dull  or  heavy  clouds  prognosticated  rain,  the  townspeople  beheld 
his  servant,  the  old  Lampe,  trudging  anxiously  behind  him  with  a 
big  umbrella  under  his  arm,  like  an  image  of  Providence. 

What  a  strange  contrast  did  this  man's  outward  life  present  to 
his  destructive,  world  annihilating  thoughts!  In  sooth,  had  the 
citizens  of  Konigsberg  had  the  least  presentiment  of  the  full  signifi 
cance  of  his  ideas,  they  would  have  felt  a  far  more  awful  dread  at 
the  presence  of  this  man  than  at  the  sight  of  an  executioner,  who 
can  but  kill  the  body.  But  the  worthy  folk  saw  in  him  nothing 
more  than  a  Professor  of  Philosophy,  and  as  he  passed  at  his 
customary  hour,  they  greeted  him  in  a  friendly  manner  and  set 
their  watches  by  him. 

But  though  Immanuel  Kant,  the  arch-destroyer  in  the  realm 
of  thought,  far  surpassed  in  terrorism  Maximilian  Robespierre,  he 
had  many  similarities  with  the  latter,  which  induce  a  comparison 
between  the  two  men.  In  the  first  place,  we  find  in  both  the  same 
inexorable,  keen,  poesyless,  sober  integrity.  We  likewise  find  in  both 
the  same  talent  of  suspicion,  only  that  in  the  one  it  manifested 
itself  in  the  direction  of  thought  and  was  called  criticism,  whilst  in 
the  other  it  was  directed  against  mankind  and  was  styled  re 
publican  virtue.  But  both  presented  in  the  highest  degree  the  type 
of  the  narrow-minded  citizen.  Nature  had  destined  them  for 
weighing  out  coffee  and  sugar,  but  fate  decided  that  they  should 
weigh  out  other  things,  and  into  the  scales  of  the  one  it  laid  a  king, 

into  the  scales  of  the  other  a  God And  they  both  gave  the 

correct  weight  ! 

The  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  is  Kant's  principal  work; 
and  as  none  of  his  other  writings  is  of  equal  importance,  in  speak 
ing  of  it  we  must  give  it  the  right  of  preference.  This  book  ap 
peared  in  1781,  but,  as  already  said,  did  not  become  generally 
known  till  1789.  At  the  time  of  its  publication  it  was  quite  over 
looked,  except  for  two  insignificant  notices,  and  it  was  not  till  a 
later  period  that  public  attention  was  directed  to  this  great  book  by 
the  articles  of  Schiitz,  Schultz,  and  Reinhold.  The  cause  of  this 
tardy  recognition  undoubtedly  lay  in  the  unusual  form  and  bad 
style  in  which  the  work  is  written.  As  regards  his  style,  Kant 
merits  severer  censure  than  any  other  philosopher,  more  especially 
when  we  compare  this  with  his  former  and  better  manner  of  writ 
ing.  The  recently  published  collection  of  his  minor  works  con- 


270  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

tains  his  first  attempts,  and  we  are  surprised  to  find  in  these  an  ex 
cellent  and  often  very  witty  style.  These  little  treatises  were  trilled 
forth  while  their  author  ruminated  over  his  great  work.  There  is 
a  gleefulness  about  them  like  that  of  a  soldier  tranquilly  arming 
for  a  combat  in  which  he  promises  himself  certain  victory.  Espe 
cially  remarkable  amongst  them  are  his  Universal  Natural  His 
tory  and  Theory  of  the  Heavens,  composed  as  early  as  1755  ; 
Observations  on  the  Emotions  of  the  Sublime  and  Beautiful 
written  ten  years  later  ;  and  Dreams  of  a  Glioststcr,  full  of 
admirable  humour  after  the  manner  of  the  French  essay.  Kant's 
wit  as  displayed  in  these  pamphlets  is  of  quite  a  peculiar  sort.  The 
wit  clings  to  the  thought,  and  in  spite  of  its  tenuity  is  thus  enable;- 
to  reach  a  satisfactory  height.  Without  such  support  wit,  be  it 
ever  so  robust,  cannot  be  successful ;  like  a  vine-tendril  wanting  a 
prop,  it  can  only  creep  along  the  ground  to  rot  there  with  all  its 
most  precious  fruits. 

But  why  did  Kant  write  his  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  in 
such  a  colourless,  dry,  packing-paper  style  ?  I  fancy  that,  having 
rejected  the  mathematical  form  of  the  Cartesio-Leibnitzo-Wolfian 
school,  he  feared  that  science  might  lose  something  of  its  dignity 
by  expressing  itself  in  light,  attractive,  and  agreeable  tones.  He 
therefore  gave  it  a  stiff,  abstract  form,  which  coldly  repelled  all 
familiarity  on  the  part  of  intellects  of  the  lower  order.  He  wished 
haughtily  to  separate  himself  from  the  popular  philosophers  of  his 
time,  who  aimed  at  the  most  citizen-like  clearness,  and  so  clothed 
his  thoughts  in  a  courtly  and  frigid  official  dialect.  Herein  he 
shows  himself  a  true  philistine.  But  it  might  also  be  that  Kant 
needed  for  the  carefully  measured  march  of  his  ideas  a  language 
similarly  precise,  and  that  he  was  not  in  a  position  to  create  a 
better.  It  is  only  genius  that  has  a  new  word  for  a  new  thought. 
Immanuel  Kant,  however,  was  no  genius.  Conscious  of  this  de 
fect,  Kant,  like  the  worthy  Maximilian,  showed  himself  all  the 
more  mistrustful  of  genius,  and  went  so  far  as  to  maintain,  in  his 
Critique  of  the  Faculty  of  Judgment,  that  genius  has  no  busi 
ness  with  scientific  thought,  and  that  its  action  ought  to  be  rele 
gated  to  the  domain  of  art. 

The  heavy,  buckram  style  of  Kant's  chief  work  has  been  the 
source  of  much  mischief ;  for  brainless  imitators  aped  him  in  his 
external  form,  and  hence  arose  amongst  us  the  superstition  that  no 
one  can  be  a  philosopher  who  writes  well.  The  mathematical 
form,  however,  could  not,  after  the  days  of  Kant,  reappear  in 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  271 

philosophy  ;  he  has  mercilessly  passed  sentence  of  death  upon  it  in 
his  Critique  of  Pure  Reason.  The  mathematical  form  in  phi 
losophy,  he  says,  is  good  for  nothing  save  the  building  of  houses 
of  cards,  in  the  same  way  that  the  philosophic  form  in  mathe 
matics  produces  nothing  but  twaddle,  for  in  philosophy  there  can 
be  no  definitions  such  as  those  in  mathematics,  where  the  defini 
tions  are  not  discursive  but  intuitive,  that  is  to  say,  capable  of  be 
ing  demonstrated  by  inspection  ;  whilst  what  are  called  definitions 
in  philosophy  are  only  tentatively,  hypothetically  put  forth,  the 
real  definition  appearing  only  at  the  close,  as  the  result. 

How  comes  it  that  philosophers  display  so  strong  a  predilec 
tion  for  the  mathematical  form  ?  This  predilection  dates  from  the 
time  of  Pythagoras,  who  designated  the  principles  of  things  by 
numbers.  This  was  the  idea  of  a  genius  :  all  that  is  sensible  and 
finite  is  stripped  off  in  a  number,  and  yet  it  denotes  something 
determined,  and  the  relation  of  this  thing  to  another  determined 
thing,  which  last,  designated  in  turn  by  a  number,  receives  the 
same  insensible  and  infinite  character.  In  this  respect  numbers  re 
semble  ideas  that  preserve  the  same  character  and  relation  to  one 
another.  We  can  indicate  by  numbers  in  a  very  striking  manner 
ideas,  as  they  are  produced  in  our  mind  and  in  nature;  but  the 
number  still  remains  the  sign  of  the  idea,  it  is  not  th-.i  idea  itself. 
The  master  is  always  conscious  of  this  distinction,  but  the  scholar 
forgets  it,  and  transmits  to  other  scholars  at  second  hand  merely  a 
numerical  hieroglyph,  dead  ciphers,  which  are  repeated  with  par 
rot-like  scholastic  pride,  but  of  which  the  living  significance  is  lost. 
This  applies  likewise  to  the  other  methods  of  mathematical  de 
monstration.  The  intellect  in  its  eternal  mobility  suffers  no  arrest; 
and  just  as  little  can  it  be  fixed  down  by  lines,  triangles,  squares, 
and  circles,  as  by  numbers.  Thought  can  neither  be  calculated 
nor  measured. 

As  my  chief  duty  is  to  facilitate  in  France  the  study  of  German 
philosophy,  I  always  dwell  most  strongly  on  the  external  difficulties 
that  are  apt  to  dismay  a  stranger  who  has  not  already  been  made 
aware  of  them.  I  would  draw  the  special  attention  of  those  who 
desire  to  make  Frenchmen  acquainted  with  Kant  to  the  fact,  that 
it  is  possible  to  abstract  from  his  philosophy  that  portion  which 
serves  merely  to  refute  the  absurdities  of  the  Wolfian  philosophy. 
This  polemic,  constantly  reappearing,  will  only  tend  to  produce 
confusion  in  the  minds  of  Frenchmen,  and  can  be  of  no  utility 
to  them. 


272  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

The  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  is,  as  I  have  said,  Kant's 
principal  work,  and  his  other  writings  are  in  a  measure  super 
fluous,  or  may  at  least  be  considered  as  commentaries.  The  social 
importance  that  attaches  to  his  chief  work  will  be  apparent  from 
what  follows. 

The  philosophers  who  preceded  Kant  reflected,  doubtless,  on 
the  origin  of  our  cognitions,  and  followed,  as  we  have  seen,  two 
different  routes,  according  to  their  view  of  ideas  as  a  priori  or  as  a 
posteriori;  but  concerning  the  faculty  of  knowing,  concerning  the 
extent  and  limits  of  this  faculty,  they  occupied  themselves  less. 
Now  this  was  the  task  that  Kant  set  before  himself  ;  he  submitted 
the  faculty  of  knowing  to  a  merciless  investigation,  he  sounded  all 
the  depths  of  this  faculty,  he  ascertained  all  its  limits.  In  this  in 
vestigation  he  certainly  discovered  that  about  many  things,  where 
with  formerly  we  supposed  ourselves  to  be  most  intimately  ac 
quainted,  we  can  know  nothing.  This  was  very  mortifying  ;  but  it 
has  always  been  useful  to  know  of  what  things  we  can  know  noth 
ing.  He  who  warns  us  against  a  useless  journey  performs  as  great 
a  service  for  us  as  he  who  points  out  to  us  the  true  path.  Kant 
proves  to  us  that  we  know  nothing  about  things  as  they  are  in  and 
by  themselves,  but  that  we  have  a  knowledge  of  them  only  in  so 
far  as  they  are  reflected  in  our  minds.  We  are  therefore  just  like 
the  prisoners  of  whose  condition  Plato  draws  such  an  afflicting 
picture  in  the  seventh  book  of  his  Republic.  These  wretched  be 
ings,  chained  neck  and  thigh  in  such  a  manner  that  they  cannot 
turn  their  heads  about,  are  seated  within  a  roofless  prison,  into 
which  there  comes  from  above  a  certain  amount  of  light.  This 
light,  however,  is  the  light  from  a  fire,  the  flame  of  which  rises  up 
behind  them,  and  indeed  is  separated  from  them  only  by  a  little 
wall.  Along  the  outer  side  of  this  wall  are  walking  men  bearing 
all  sorts  of  statues,  images  in  wood  and  stone,  and  conversing  with 
one  another.  Now  the  poor  prisoners  can  see  nothing  of  these 
men,  who  are  not  tall  enough  to  overtop  the  wall ;  and  of  the 
statues,  which  rise  above  the  wall,  they  see  only  the  shadows  flit 
ting  along  the  side  of  the  wall  opposite  them.  The  shadows,  how 
ever,  they  take  for  real  objects,  and,  deceived  by  the  echo  of  their 
prison,  believe  that  it  is  the  shadows  that  are  conversing. 

With  the  appearance  of  Kant  former  systems  of  philosophy, 
which  had  merely  sniffed  about  the  external  aspect  of  things,  as 
sembling  and  classifying  their  characteristics,  ceased  to  exist.  Kant 
led  investigation  back  to  the  human  intellect,  and  inquired  what 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  273 

the  latter  had  to  reveal.  Not  without  reason,  therefore,  did  he 
compare  his  philosophy  to  the  method  of  Copernicus.  Formerly 
when  men  conceived  the  world  as  standing  still,  and  the  sun  as 
revolving  round  it,  astronomical  calculations  failed  to  agree  ac 
curately.  But  wrhen  Copernicus  made  the  sun  stand  still  and  the 
earth  revolve  round  it,  behold !  everything  accorded  admirably. 
So  formerly  reason,  like  the  sun,  moved  round  the  universe  of 
phenomena,  and  sought  to  throw  light  upon  it.  But  Kant  bade 
reason,  the  sun,  stand  still,  and  the  universe  of  phenomena  now 
turns  round,  and  is  illuminated  the  moment  it  comes  within  the 
region  of  the  intellectual  orb. 

These  few  words  regarding  the  task  that  presented  itself  to 
Kant  will  suffice  to  show  that  I  consider  that  section  of  his  book 
where  he  treats  of  phenomena  and  noumena  as  the  most  impor 
tant  part,  as  the  central  point,  of  his  philosophy.  Kant,  in  effect, 
distinguishes  between  the  appearances  of  things  and  things  them 
selves.  As  we  can  know  nothing  of  objects  except  in  so  far  as 
they  manifest  themselves  to  us  through  their  appearance,  and  as 
objects  do  not  exhibit  themselves  to  us  as  they  are  in  and  by 
themselves,  Kant  gives  the  name  phenomena  to  objects  as  they 
appear  to  us,  and  noumena  to  objects  as  they  are  in  themselves. 
We  know  things,  therefore,  only  as  phenomena ;  we  cannot  know 
them  as  noumena.  The  latter  are  purely  problematic;  we  can 
neither  say  that  they  exist  nor  that  they  do  not  exist.  The  word 
noumena  has  been  correlated  with  the  word  phenomena  merely 
to  enable  us  to  speak  of  things  in  so  far  as  they  are  cognisable 
by  us,  without  occupying  our  judgment  about  things  that  are  not 
cognisable  by  us.  Kant  did  not  therefore,  as  do  many  teachers 
whom  I  will  not  name,  make  a  distinction  of  objects  into  phe 
nomena  and  noumena,  into  things  that  for  us  exist  and  into 
things  that  for  us  do  not  exist.  This  would  be  an  Irish  bull  in 
philosophy.  He  wished  merely  to  express  a  notion  of  limitation. 

God,  according  to  Kant,  is  a  noumenon.  As  a  result  of  his 
argument,  this  ideal  and  transcendental  being,  hitherto  called 
God,  is  a  mere  fiction.  It  has  arisen  from  a  natural  illusion.  Kant 
shows  that  we  can  know  nothing  regarding  this  noumenon,  re 
garding  God,  and  that  all  reasonable  proof  of  his  existence  is  im 
possible.  The  words  of  Dante,  "Leave  all  hope  behind  !"  may  be 
inscribed  over  this  portion  of  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason. 

My  readers  will,  I  think,  gladly  exempt  me  from  attempting  a 
popular  elucidation  of  that  portion  of  his  work  in  which  Kant 


274  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

treats  "  of  the  arguments  of  speculative  reason  in  favour  of  the  ex 
istence  of  a  Supreme  Being."  Although  the  formal  refutation  of 
these  arguments  occupies  but  a  small  space,  and  is  not  taken  in 
hand  till  the  second  part  of  the  book  is  reached,  there  is  already  a 
very  evident  intention  of  leading  up  to  this  refutation,  which  forms 
one  of  the  main  points  of  the  work.  It  connects  itself  with  the 
Critique  of  all  Speculative  Theology,  wherein  the  last  phan 
toms  of  deism  are  put  to  flight.  I  cannot  help  remarking  that 
Kant,  in  attacking  the  three  principal  kinds  of  evidence  in  favour 
of  the  existence  of  God,  namely,  the  ontological,  the  cosmological, 
and  the  physico-theological,  whilst  successful,  according  to  my 
opinion,  in  refuting  the  latter  two,  fails  with  regard  to  the  first.  I 
am  not  aware  whether  the  above  terms  are  understood  in  this 
country,  and  I  therefore  quote  the  passage  from  the  Critique  of 
Pure  Reason  in  which  Kant  formulates  the  distinction  between 
them. 

"  There  are  but  three  kinds  of  proof  possible  to  speculative 
reason  of  the  existence  of  God.  All  the  routes  that  may  be  selected 
with  this  end  in  view  start,  either  from  definite  experience  and  the 
peculiar  properties  of  the  external  world,  as  revealed  by  experi 
ence,  and  ascend  from  it  according  to  the  laws  of  causality  up  to 
the  supreme  cause  above  the  world  ;  or,  they  rest  merely  on  an 
indefinite  experience,  as,  for  example,  on  an  existence  or  being  of 
some  kind  or  other  ;  or,  lastly,  they  make  an  abstraction  from  all 
experience,  and  arrive  at  a  conclusion  entirely  a  priori  from  pure 
ideas  of  the  existence  of  the  supreme  cause.  The  first  of  these  is 
the  physico-theological  proof,  the  second  the  cosmological,  and  the 
third  the  ontological.  Other  proofs  there  are  none,  nor  can  other 
proofs  exist." 

After  repeated  and  careful  study  of  Kant's  chief  work,  I  fan 
cied  myself  able  to  recognise  everywhere  visible  in  it  his  polemic 
? gainst  these  proofs  of  the  existence  of  God  ;  and  of  this  polemic  I 
might  speak  at  greater  length  were  I  not  restrained  by  a  religious 
sentiment.  The  mere  discussion  by  any  one  of  the  existence  of 
God  causes  me  to  feel  a  strange  disquietude,  an  uneasy  dread  such 
as  I  once  experienced  in  visiting  New  Bedlam  in  London,  when, 
for  a  moment  losing  sight  of  my  guide,  I  was  surrounded  by  mad 
men.  "  God  is  all  that  is,"  and  doubt  of  His  existence  is  doubt  of 
life  itself,  it  is  death. 

The  more  blameworthy  any  dispute  regarding  the  existence  ol 
God  may  be,  the  more  praiseworthy  is  meditation  on  the  nature  .of 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  275 

God.  Such  meditation  is  a  true,  worship  of  God ;  the  soul  is 
thereby  detached  from  the  perishable  and  finite,  and  attains  to 
consciousness  of  innate  love  and  of  the  harmony  of  the  universe. 
It  is  this  consciousness  that  sends  a  thrill  through  the  heart  of  the 
emotional  man  in  the  act  of  prayer  or  in  the  contemplation  of  the 
sacred  symbols  ;  and  the  thinker  realises  this  holy  fervour  in  t*ie 
exercise  of  that  sublime  faculty  of  the  mind  called  reason,  a  facu'iy 
whose  highest  function  is  to  inquire  into  the  nature  of  God.  Mi;n 
of  specially  religious  temperament  concern  themselves  with  this 
problem  from  childhood  upwards ;  they  are  mysteriously  troubled 
about  it  even  at  the  first  dawnings  of  reason.  The  author  of  these 
pages  is  most  joyfully  conscious  of  having  possessed  this  early 
primitive  religious  feeling,  and  it  has  never  forsaken  him.  God 
was  always  the  beginning  and  the  end  of  all  my  thoughts.  If  I 
now  inquire  :  What  is  God  ?  what  is  his  nature  ? — as  a  little  child 
I  had  already  inquired  :  How  is  God  ?  what  is  he  like  ?  In  that 
childish  time  I  could  gaze  upwards  at  the  sky  during  whole  days, 
and  was  sadly  vexed  at  evening  because  I  never  caught  a  glimpse 
of  God's  most  holy  countenance,  but  saw  only  the  grey  silly  gri 
maces  of  the  clouds.  I  was  quite  puzzled  over  the  astronomical 
lore  with  which  in  the  "enlightenment  period  "  even  the  youngest 
children  were  tormented,  and  there  was  no  end  to  my  amazement 
on  learning  that  all  those  thousand  millions  of  stars  were  spheres 
as  large  and  as  beautiful  as  our  own  earth,  and  that  over  all  this 
glittering  throng  of  worlds  a  single  God  ruled.  I  recollect  once 
seeing  God  in  a  dream  far  above  in  the  most  distant  firmament. 
He  was  looking  contentedly  out  of  a  little  window  in  the  sky,  a 
devout  hoary-headed  being  with  a  small  Jewish  beard,  and  he  was 
scattering  forth  myriads  of  seed-corns,  which,  as  they  fell  from 
heaven,  burst  open  in  the  infinitude  of  space,  and  expanded  to  vast 
dimensions  till  they  became  actual,  radiant,  blossoming,  peopled 
worlds,  each  one  as  large  as  our  own  globe.  I  could  never  forget 
this  countenance,  and  often  in  dreams  I  used  to  see  the  cheerful- 
looking  old  man  sprinkling  forth  the  world-seeds  from  his  little 
window  in  the  sky;  once  I  even  saw  him  clucking  like  our  maid 
when  she  threw  down  for  the  hens  their  barley.  I  could  only  see 
how  the  falling  seed-corns  expanded  into  great  shining  orbs  :  but 
the  great  hens  that  may  by  chance  have  been  waiting  about  with 
eager  open  bills  to  be  fed  with  the  falling  orbs  I  could  not  see. 

You  smile,  dear  reader,  at  the  notion  of  the  big  hens.    Yet  this 
childish  notion  is  not  so  very  different  from  the  view  of  the  most 


276  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

advanced  deists.  In  the  attempt  to  provide  a  conception  of  an  ex 
tra-mundane  God,  orient  and  Occident  have  exhausted  themselves 
in  hyperbole.  The  imagination  of  deists  has,  however,  vainly  tor 
mented  itself  with  the  infinitude  of  time  and  space.  It  is  here  that 
their  impotence,  the  inadequacy  of  their  cosmology,  and  the  unten- 
ableness  of  their  explanation  of  the  nature  of  God  becomes  fully  ap 
parent.  We  are  not  greatly  distressed,  therefore,  at  beholding  the 
subversion  of  their  explanation.  Kant  has  actually  wrought  this 
affliction  upon  them  by  refuting  their  demonstration  of  the  exist 
ence  of  God. 

Nor  would  the  vindication  of  the  ontological  proof  specially 
benefit  deism,  for  this  proof  is  equally  available  for  pantheism. 
To  render  my  meaning  more  intelligible,  I  may  remark  that  the 
ontological  proof  is  the  one  employed  by  Descartes,  and  that  long 
before  his  time,  in  the  Middle  Ages,  Anselm  of  Canterbury  had  ex 
pressed  it  in  the  form  of  an  affecting  prayer.  Indeed,  St.  Augustine 
may  be  said  to  have  already  made  use  of  the  ontological  proof  in 
the  second  book  of  his  work,  De  Libero  Arbitrio. 

I  refrain,  as  I  have  said,  from  all  popular  discussion  of  Kant's 
polemic  against  these  proofs.  Let  it  suffice  to  give  an  assurance 
that  since  his  time  deism  has  vanished  from  the  realm  of  specu 
lative,  reason.  It  may,  perhaps,  be  several  centuries  yet  before 
this  melancholy  notice  of  decease  gets  universally  bruited  about; 
we,  however,  have  long  since  put  on  mourning.  De  Profundis! 

You  fancy,  then,  that  we  may  now  go  home  !  By  my  life,  no! 
there  is  yet  a  piece  to  be  played ;  after  the  tragedy  comes  the 
farce.  Up  to  this  point  Immanuel  Kant  has  pursued  the  path  of 
inexorable  philosophy  ;  he  has  stormed  heaven  and  put  the  whole 
garrison  to  the  edge  of  the  sword  ;  the  ontological,  cosmological, 
and  physico  theological  bodyguards  lie  there  lifeless;  Deity  itself, 
deprived  of  demonstration,  has  succumbed;  there  is  now  no  All- 
mercifulness,  no  fatherly  kindness,  no  other-world  reward  for  re 
nunciation  in  this  world,  the  immortality  of  the  soul  lies  in  its  last 
agony — you  can  hear  its  groans  and  death-rattle  ;  and  old  Lampe 
is  standing  by  with  his  umbrella  under  his  arm,  an  afflicted  spec 
tator  of  the  scene,  tears  and  sweat-drops  of  terror  dropping  from 
his  countenance.  Then  Immanuel  Kant  relents  and  shows  that  he 
is  not  merely  a  great  philosopher  but  also  a  good  man  ;  he  reflects, 
and  half  good-naturedly,  half  ironically,  he  says:  "Old  Lampe 
must  have  a  God,  otherwise  the  poor  fellow  can  never  be  happy. 
Now,  man  ought  to  be  happy  in  this  world  ;  practical  reason  says 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  277 

so ; — well,  I  am  quite  willing  that  practical  reason  should  also 
guarantee  the  existence  of  God."  As  the  result  of  this  argument 
Kant  distinguishes  between  the  theoretical  reason  and  the  practi 
cal  reason,  and  by  means  of  the  latter,  as  with  a  magician's  wand, 
he  revivifies  deism,  which  theoretical  reason  had  killed. 

But  is  it  not  conceivable  that  Kant  brought  about  this  resur 
rection,  not  merely  for  the  sake  of  old  Lampe,  but  through  fear  of 
the  police?  Or  did  he  act  from  sincere  conviction?  Was  not  his 
object  in  destroying  all  evidence  for  the  existence  of  God  to  show 
us  how  embarrassing  it  might  be  to  know  nothing  about  God  ?  In 
doing  so,  he  acted  almost  as  sagely  as  a  Westphalian  friend  of 
mine,  who  smashed  all  the  lanterns  in  the  Grohnder  Street  in  Got- 
tingen,  and  then  proceeded  to  deliver  to  us  in  the  dark  a  long 
lecture  on  the  practical  necessity  of  lanterns,  which  he  had  the 
oretically  broken  in  order  to  show  how,  without  them,  we  could 
see  nothing. 

I  have  already  said  that  on  its  appearance  the  Critique  of 
Pure  Reason  did  not  cause  the  slightest  sensation,  and  it  was  not 
till  several  years  later,  after  certain  clear-sighted  philosophers  had 
written  elucidations  of  it,  that  public  attention  was  aroused  regard 
ing  the  book.  In  the  year  1789,  however,  nothing  else  was  talked 
of  in  Germany  but  the  philosophy  of  Kant,  about  which  were 
poured  forth  in  abundance  commentaries,  chrestomathies,  inter 
pretations,  estimates,  apologies,  and  so  forth.  We  need  only  glance 
through  the  first  philosophic  catalogue  at  hand,  and  the  innumer 
able  works  having  reference  to  Kant  will  amply  testify  to  the  in 
tellectual  movement  that  originated  with  this  single  man.  In  some 
it  exhibited  itself  as  an  ardent  enthusiasm,  in  others  as  an  acrid 
loTthing,  in  many  as  a  gaping  curiosity  regarding  the  result  of  this 
intellectual  revolution.  We  had  popular  riots  in  the  world  of 
thought,  just  as  you  had  in  the  material  world,  and  over  the  dem 
olition  of  ancient  dogmatism  we  grew  as  excited  as  you  did  at  the 
Storming  of  the  Bastille.  There  was  also  but  a  handful  of  old  pen 
sioners  left  for  the  defence  of  dogmatism,  that  is,  the  philosophy 
of  Wolf.  It  was  a  revolution,  and  one  not  wanting  in  horrors. 
Amor.pst  the  party  of  the  past,  the  really  good  Christians  showed 
least  indignation  at  these  horrors.  Yea,  they  desired  even  greater, 
in  order  that  the  measure  of  iniquity  might  be  full,  and  the  coun 
ter-revolution  be  more  speedily  accomplished  as  a  necessary  re 
action.  We  had  pessimists  in  philosophy  as  you  had  in  politics. 
As  in  France  there  were  people  who  maintained  that  Robespierre 


278  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

was  the  agent  of  Pitt,  with  us  there  were  many  who  went  so  far  in 
their  wilful  blindness  as  to  persuade  themselves  that  Kant  was  in 
secret  alliance  with  them,  and  that  he  had  destroyed  all  philo 
sophic  proofs  of  the  existence  of  God  merely  in  order  to  convince 
the  world  that  man  can  never  arrive  at  a  knowledge  of  God  by  the 
help  of  reason,  and  must  therefore  hold  to  revealed  religion. 

Kant  brought  about  this  great  intellectual  movement  less  by 
the  subject-matter  of  his  writings  than  by  the  critical  spirit  that 
pervaded  them,  a  spirit  that  now  began  to  force  its  way  into  all 
sciences.  It  laid  hold  of  all  constituted  authority.  Even  poetry 
did  not  escape  its  influence.  Schiller,  for  example,  was  a  strong 
Kantist,  and  his  artistic  views  are  impregnated  with  the  spirit  of 
the  philosophy  of  Kant.  By  reason  of  its  dry,  abstract  character, 
this  philosophy  was  eminently  hurtful  to  polite  literature  and  the 
fine  arts  Fortunately  it  did  not  interfere  in  the  art  of  cookery. 

The  German  people  is  not  easily  set  in  motion  ;  but  let  it  be 
once  forced  into  any  path  and  it  will  follow  it  to  its  termination 
with  the  most  dogged  perseverance.  Thus  we  exhibited  our  char- 
icter  in  matters  of  religion,  thus  also  we  now  acted  in  philosophy. 
Shall  we  continue  to  advance  as  consistently  in  politics  ? 

Germany  was  drawn  into  the  path  of  philosophy  by  Kant,  and 
philosophy  became  a  national  cause.  A  brilliant  troop  of  great 
thinkers  suddenly  sprang  up  on  German  soil,  as  if  called  into  be 
ing  by  magical  art.  If  German  philosophy  should  some  day  find, 
as  the  French  revolution  has  found,  its  Thiers  and  its  Mignet,  its 
history  will  afford  as  remarkable  reading  as  the  works  of  these 
authors.  Germans  will  study  it  with  pride,  and  Frenchmen  with 
admiration. 


THE  KANTIAN  PHILOSOPHY. 
(AFTER  ARTHUR  SCHOPENHAUER.') 

KANT'S  greatest  merit  is  the  distinction  of  the  phenomenon 
from  the  thing  in  itself,  based  upon  the  proof  that  between 
things  and  us  there  still  always  stands  the  intellect,  so  that  they 
cannot  be  known  as  they  may  be  in  themselves.  He  was  led  into 
this  path  through  Locke  (see  Prolegomena,  §  13,  Note  2).  The 
latter  had  shown  that  the  secondary  qualities  of  things,  such  as 
sound,  smell,  color,  hardness,  softness,  smoothness,  and  the  like, 
as  founded  on  the  affections  of  the  senses,  do  not  belong  to  the 
objective  body,  to  the  thing  in  itself.  To  this  he  attributed  only 
the  primary  qualities,  i.  e.,  such  as  only  presuppose  space  and  im 
penetrability  ;  thus  extension,  figure,  solidity,  number,  mobility. 
But  this  easily  discovered  Lockeian  distinction  was,  as  it  were, 
only  a  youthful  introduction  to  the  distinction  of  Kant.  The  lat 
ter,  starting  from  an  incomparably  higher  standpoint,  explains  all 
that  Locke  had  accepted  as  primary  qualities,  i.  e.,  qualities  of 
the  thing  in  itself,  as  also  belonging  only  to  its  phenomenal  ap 
pearance  in  our  faculty  of  apprehension,  and  this  just  because  the 
conditions  of  this  faculty,  space,  time  and  causality,  are  known  by 
us  a  priori.  Thus  Locke  had  abstracted  from  the  thing  in  itself 
the  share  which  the  organs  of  sense  have  in  its  phenomenal  ap 
pearance  ;  Kant,  however,  further  abstracted  the  share  of  the 
brain-functions  (though  not  under  that  name).  Thus  the  distinc 
tion  between  the  phenomenon  and  the  thing  in  itself  now  received 
an  infinitely  greater  significance  and  a  very  much  deeper  meaning. 
For  this  end  he  was  obliged  to  take  in  hand  the  important  separa 
tion  of  our  a  priori  from  our  a  posteriori  knowledge  which  be 
fore  him  had  never  been  carried  out  with  adequate  strictness  and 
completeness,  nor  with  distinct  consciousness.  Accordingly  this 

IFrom   the    World  as    Will  and  Idea.    Trans,  by  Haldane  and   Kemp. 
3  vols.    Third  edition.     London:   Kegan  Paul,  Trench,  Triibner  &  Co.     1896. 


280  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

-  •» 

f  < 

now  became  the  principal  subject  of  his  profound  investigations 
Now  here  we  would  at  once  remark  thit  Kant's  philosophy  has  a 
threefold  relation  to  that  of  his  predecessors.  First,  as  we  have 
just  seen,  to  the  philosophy  of  Locke,  confirming  and  extending 
it;  secondly,  to  that  of  Hume,  correcting  and  making  use  of  it,  a 
relation  which  is  most  distinctly  expressed  in  the  Prolegomena 
(that  most  beautiful  and  comprehensible  of  all  Kant's  important 
writings,  which  is  far  too  little  read,  for  it  facilitates  immensely 
the  study  of  b;s  philosophy),  thirdly,  a  decidedly  polemical  and 
destructive  relation  to  the  Leibnitz-Wolfian  philosophy.  All  three 
systems  ought  to  be  known  before  one  proceeds  to  the  study  of  the 
Kantian  philosophy.  Now  as  Kant's  separation  of  the  phenome 
non  from  the  thing  in  itself,  arrived  at  in  the  manner  explained 
above,  far  surpassed  all  that  preceded  it  in  the  depth  and  thonght- 
fulness  of  its  conception,  it  was  also  exceedingly  important  in  its 
results.  For  in  it  he  propounded,  quite  originally,  in  a  perfectly 
new  way,  found  from  a  new  side  and  on  a  new  path,  the  same 
truth  which  Plato  never  wearies  of  repeating,  and  in  his  language 
generally  expresses  thus:  This  world  which  appears  to  the  senses 
has  no  true  being,  but  only  a  ceaseless  becoming;  it  is,  and  it  is 
not,  and  its  comprehension  is  not  so  much  knowledge  as  illusion. 
This  is  also  what  he  expresses  mythically  at  the  beginning  of  the 
seventh  book  of  the  Republic,  which  is  the  most  important  passage 
in  all  his  writings.  He  says:  "Men,  firmly  chained  in  a  dark 
cave,  see  neither  the  true  original  light  nor  real  things,  but  only 
the  meagre  light  of  the  fire  in  the  cave  and  the  shadows  of  real 
things  which  pass  by  the  fire  behind  their  backs;  yet  they  think 
the  shadows  are  the  reality,  and  the  determining  of  the  succession 
of  these  shadows  is  true  wisdom."  The  same  truth,  again  quite 
differently  presented,  is  also  a  leading  doctrine  of  the  Vedas  and 
Puranas,  the  doctrine  of  Maya,  by  which  really  nothing  else  is 
understood  than  what  Kant  calls  the  phenomenon  in  opposition  to 
the  thing  in  itself;  for  the  work  of  Miya  is  said  to  be  just  this 
visible  world  in  which  we  are,  a  summoned  enchantment,  an  in 
constant  appearance  without  true  being,  like  an  optical  illusion  or 
a  dream,  a  veil  which  surrounds  human  consciousness,  something 
of  which  it  is  equally  false  and  true  to  say  that  it  is  and  that  it  is 
not.  But  Kant  not  only  expressed  the  same  doctrine  in  a  com 
pletely  new  and  original  way,  but  raised  it  to  the  position  of  proved 
and  indisputable  truth  by  means  of  the  calmest  and  most  tempe 
rate  exposition;  while  both  Plato  and  the  Indian  philosophers  had 


KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  281 

founded  their  assertions  merely  upon  a  general  perception  of  the 
world,  bad  advanced  them  as  the  direct  utterance  of  their  con 
sciousness,  and  presented  them  rather  mythically  and  poetically 
than  philosophically  and  distinctly.  In  this  respect  they  stand  to 
Kant  in  the  same  relation  as  the  Pythagoreans  Hicetas,  Philolaus, 
and  Aristarchus,  who  already  asserted  the  movement  of  the  earth 
round  the  fixed  sun,  stand  to  Copernicus.  Such  distinct  knowl 
edge  and  calm,  thoughtful  exposition  of  this  dream-like  nature  of 
the  whole  world  is  really  the  basis  of  the  whole  Kantian  philoso 
phy  ;  it  is  its  soul  and  its  greatest  merit.  He  accomplished  this 
by  taking  to  pieces  the  whole  machinery  of  our  intellect  by  means 
of  which  the  phantasmagoria  of  the  objective  world  is  brought 
about,  and  presenting  it  in  detail  with  marvellous  insight  and  abil 
ity.  All  earlier  Western  philosophy,  appearing  in  comparison  with 
the  Kantian  unspeakably  clumsy,  had  failed  to  recognise  that 
truth,  and  had  therefore  always  spoken  just  as  if  in  a  dream. 
Kant  first  awakened  it  suddenly  out  of  this  dream  ;  therefore  the 
last  sleepers  (Mendelssohn)  called  him  the  "all-destroyer."  He 
show,  d  that  the  laws  which  reign  with  inviolable  necessity  in  ex 
istence,  i.  e.,  in  experience  generally,  are  not  to  be  applied  to  de 
duce  and  explain  existence  itself;  that  thus  the  validity  of  these 
laws  is  only  relative,  i.  e.,  only  arises  after  existence;  the  world 
of  experience  in  general  is  already  established  and  present ;  that 
consequently  these  laws  cannot  be  our  guide  when  we  come  to  the 
explanation  of  the  existence  of  the  world  and  of  ourselves.  All 
earlier  Western  philosophers  had  imagined  that  these  laws,  ac 
cording  to  which  the  phenomena  are  combined,  and  all  of  which — 
time  and  space,  as  well  as  causality  and  inference — I  comprehend 
under  the  expression  "the  principle  of  sufficient  reason," — were 
absolute  laws  conditioned  by  nothing,  ccternce  ventatcs  \  that  the 
world  itself  existed  only  in  consequence  of  and  in  conformity  with 
them  ;  and  therefore  that  under  their  guidance  the  whole  riddle  of 
the  world  must  be  capable  of  solution.  The  assumptions  made 
for  this  purpose,  which  Kant  criticises  under  the  name  of  the  Idecs 
of  the  reason,  only  served  to  raise  the  mere  phenomenon,  the  work 
of  Maya,  the  shadow  world  of  Plato,  to  the  one  highest  reality,  to 
put  it  in  the  place  of  the  inmost  and  true  being  of  things,  and 
thereby  to  make  the  real  knowledge  of  this  impossible;  that  is,  in 
a  word,  to  send  the  dreamers  still  more  soundly  to  sleep.  Kant 
exhibited  these  laws,  and  therefore  the  whole  world,  as  conditioned 
by  the  form  of  knowledge  belonging  to  the  subject ;  from  which  it 


282  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

followed,  that  however  far  one  carried  investigation  and  reasoning 
under  the  guidance  of  these  laws,  yet  in  the  principal  matter,  i.  e., 
in  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  the  world  in  itself  and  outside  the 
idea,  no  step  in  advance  was  made,  but  one  only  moved  like  a 
squirrel  in  its  wheel.  Thus,  all  the  dogmatists  may  be  compared 
to  persons  who  supposed  that  if  they  only  went  straight  on  long 
enough  they  would  come  to  the  end  of  the  world ;  but  Kant  then 
circumnavigated  the  world  and  showed  that,  because  it  is  round, 
one  cannot  get  out  of  it  by  horizontal  movement,  but  that  yet  by 
perpendicular  movement  this  is  perhaps  not  impossible.  We  may 
also  say  that  Kant's  doctrine  affords  the  insight  that  we  must  seek 
the  end  and  beginning  of  the  world,  not  without,  but  within  us. 


AN  ESTIMATE  OF  KANT  BY  A  SWEDEN- 
BORGIAN. 

(AFTER  THEODORE  F.  WRIGHT.') 

IN  all  his  metaphysical  work  Kant  was  not  pursuing  a  religious 
course  and  was  in  fact  becoming  less  and  less  of  a  Christian. 
He  was,  however,  no  more  contracted  in  his  philosophical  view  of 
the  limits  of  reason  than  he  was  in  all  the  ways  of  his  life.  "  His 
body  was  extremely  emaciated,  and  at  last  it  was  dried  like  a  pot 
sherd,"  said  one  who  knew  him  well.  He  was  hollow-chested,  and 
one  shoulder  was  too  low.  Not  five  feet  high,  his  bones  were 
small  and  weak,  and  bis  muscles  still  weaker  (Stiickenburg,  p.  93). 
He  had  strong  prejudice  against  the  Jews  (Jbid.,  p.  116).  He  took 
no  interest  in  other  philosophers  (Ibid.,  p.  124).  Though  be  wrote 
much  in  the  field  of  theology,  he  knew  almost  nothing  of  theolo 
gians  (Ibid.,  p.  359).  He  did  not  answer  letters  (1 bid.,  p.  127). 
He  held  to  his  views  after  rebutting  facts  were  shown  him,  and 
would  contradict  foreigners  who  spoke  of  their  own  countries  in  a 
manner  to  interfere  with  his  preconceived  ideas  (Ibid.,  p.  141). 
He  lived  in  the  same  small  city  with  his  two  sisters,  yet  did  not 
speak  to  them  for  twenty-five  years  because  of  their  inferior  posi 
tion  (Ibid.,  p.  182).  He  spoke  contemptuously  of  women  and  \vas 
especially  hostile  to  those  of  any  mental  power  (Ibid  ,  p  784).  Ore 
of  his  jokes  was  that  there  can  be  no  women  in  heaven,  for  it  is 
written  that  there  was  silence  there  for  the  space  of  half  an  hour 
(Ibid.,  p.  187), — and  this  from  a  man  who  always  did  the  talking 
wherever  he  was  and  who  listened  to  another  with  marked  impa 
tience  (Ibid.,  p.  141).  He  did  not  desire  friendships,  for  "  it  is  a 
great  burden  to  be  tied  to  the  fate  of  others  and  to  be  loaded  with 
their  needs "  (Ibid. ,  p.  193).  He  said  that  he  did  not  know  the 
meaning  of  the  word  "  spirit"  (Ibid.,  p.  240).  With  Hume  he  held 

IThis  amusing  compilation  of  data  concerning  Kant's  life  and  personal 
ity  appeared  in  the  New  Church  Review  (Boston)  of  January,  1901. 


284  KANT'S  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

that  we  have  no  knowledge  of  God  (Ibid.,  p.  290).  He  saw  no 
use  in  revelation  (Ibid.,  p.  335).  H-3  identified  religion  with  mere 
morality  (Ibid.,  p.  338).  He  never  attended  church  and  spoke  of 
prayer  as  ridiculous  (Ibid  ,  p.  354).  His  views  against  religion 
led  students  to  become  mockers  (Ibid.,  p.  358).  His  old  age  was 
unhappy  (Ibid.,  p.  425),  and  his  rigidity  of  habits  became  repul 
sive  in  the  last  degree  (Ibid.,  p.  435).  He  died  February  12,  1804, 
after  fifteen  years  of  mental  decline. 


KANT'S  LETTER  TO  HIS  BROTHER.1 

TRANSCRIPTION  OF  THE  ORIGINAL. 

Lieber  Bruder ! 

Bei  dem  Besuche,  den  Ueberbringer  dieses,  Herr  Reimer,  ein 
Verwandter  von  Deiner  Frau,  meiner  werthen  Schwagerin,  bei 
mir  ab»elegt  hat,  ermangle  ich  nicht,  was  sich  meiner  iiberhauften 
Beschaftigungen  wegen  nur  in  ausserordentlichen  Fallen  thun 
lasst,  mich  bei  Dir  durch  einen  Brief  in  Erinnerung  zu  bringen. 
Unerachtet  dieser  scheinbaren  Gleichgtiltigkeit  habe  ich  an  Dich, 
nicht  allein  so  lange  wir  beiderseitig  leben,  oft  genug,  sondern 
auch  fur  meinen  Sterbefall,  der  in  meinem  Alter  von  68  Jahren 
doch  nicht  mehr  sehr  entfernt  sein  kann,  briiderlich  gedacht. 
Unsere  zwei  iibrigen,  beide  verwittweten,  Schwestern  sind,  die 
alteste,  welche  fiinf  erwachsene  und  zura  Theil  schon  verhei- 
rathete  Kinder  bat,  ganzlich  durch  mich,  die  andere,  welche  im 
St.  Georgenhospital  eingekauft  ist,  durch  meinen  Zuschuss  ver- 
sorgt.  Den  Kindern  der  ersteren  habe  ich,  bei  ihrer  anfanglichen 
hauslichen  Einrichtung  und  auch  nacbher,  meinen  Beistand  nicht 
versagt;  so  dass,  was  die  Pflicht  der  Dankbarkeit,  \vegen  der  uns 
von  unsern  gemeinschaftlichen  Eltern  gewordenen  Erziehnng  for- 
dert,  nicht  versSumt  wird.  Wenn  Du  mir  einmal  von  dem  Zu- 
stande  Deiner  eigenen  Familie  Nachricht  geben  willst,  so  wird  es 
mir  angenehm  sein. 

Uebrigens  bin  ich,  in  Begriissung  meiner  mir  sehr  wertben 
Schwagerin,  mit  unveranderlicher  Zuneigung 

Dein  treuer  Bruder 

KONIGSBERG,  den  26.  Januar  1792.  I.  KANT. 

TRANSLATION. 
DEAR  BROTHER: — 

Taking  advantage  of  the  visit  which  the  bearer  of  this  letter 
Herr  Reimer,  a  relative  of  your  wife,  my  esteemed  sister-in-law 

iSee  the  facsimile  of  the  German  original  on  the  opposite  page. 


286  KANT'S  LETTER  TO  HIS  BROTHER. 

has  paid  me,  I  do  not  omit  to  recall  myself  to  your  memory, 
although  owing  to  my  over-burdening  labors  this  is  something  that 
I  allow  myself  only  in  extraordinary  cases.  Notwithstanding  this 
apparent  indifference,  I  have,  however,  frequently  thought  of  you 
with  brotherly  regard,  not  only  for  this  present  life,  but  also  in 
case  of  my  death,  which  at  my  age  of  68  years  cannot  be  far  dis 
tant.  Of  our  two  remaining  widowed  sisters,  the  eldest,  who  has 
five  adult  children,  some  of  whom  are  married,  has  been  entirely 
supported  by  me,  and  the  younger,  for  whom  admission  to  the  St. 
George's  Hospital  has  been  purchased,  is  also  provided  for.  I 
have  also  not  refused  assistance  to  the  children  of  the  former,  on 
their  establishing  their  first  homes,  and  even  afterwards ;  so  that 
there  has  been  no  neglect  of  the  duty  of  gratitude  that  we  owe  to 
our  common  parents  for  the  education  they  gave  us.  If  you  will 
inform  me  of  the  condition  of  your  own  family,  I  shall  be  gratified. 

With  regards  to  my  much-esteemed  sister-in-law,  I  remain, 
with  constant  affection, 

Your  Faithful  Brother, 

I.  KANT. 

KONIGSBKRG,  January  26,  1792. 


CHRONOLOGY  OF  KANT'S   LIFE   AND   PUB 
LICATIONS.1 


1724  Immanuel  Kant  born  on 
April  22. 

1728  Lambert  born. 

1729  Lessing  born. 

1729  Mendelssohn  born. 

1730  Hamann  born. 

1732  Kant  enters  the  Frideri- 
ciannm,  an  academy  in 
KOnigsberg. 

1735  Kant's  brother  Johann 
Heinrich  born. 

1737  Kant's  mother  dies. 
1740  Kant  matriculates   at   the 
University  of  Konigsberg 

1740  Frederick  II.  ascends 
the  throne. 

1740  Feder  born. 

1742  Garve  born. 

1744  Herder  born. 
1746  Kant's  first  publication  : 
Gtdanken  von  der  vjah- 
ren  Schatzung  der  leben- 
digen  Krdfte  (Thoughts 
on  the  True  Measure 
ment  of  Living  Forces). 

1746  Kant's  father  dies. 

1749  Goethe  born. 

1751  M.  Knutzen  dies. 

1754  Christian  Wolff  dies. 


1754  Investigation  of  the  ques 

tion,  Whether  the  earth 
in  its  rotation  about  its 
axis  has  suffered  any  al 
terations. 

1754.  Investigation  of  the  ques 
tion,  Whether  the  earth 
is  growing  old.  (Both 
questions  treated  in  the 
KSnigsberger  Nachr.}. 

1755  AUgcm.   Naturgeschichte 

und  Theorie  des  Him- 
mels  (General  Natural 
History  and  Theory  of 
the  Heavens). 

1755  Kant  takes  his  degree  with 

the  treatise  De  Jgnc,  and 
qualifies  as  a  university 
lecturer  with  the  treatise, 
Princi-piorumprimorum 
cognitionis  mcta-physicce 
nova  dilucidatio. 
1756-1763  Seven  Years 
War.  The  Russians  in 
KSnigsberg. 

1756  Disputation  on  the  treatise 

Monadologia  physica. 
1756  Three  small  essays  in  the 
Kdnigsberger     Nachr., 


1  From  Paulsen's  Life  of  Kant,  Fromann's  Klassiker  der  Philasofhi€t  Stutt 
gart,  1898. 


288 


CHRONOLOGY. 


on  Earthquakes.  (Evoked 
by  the  Lisbon  earthquake 

0*  I755-) 

1756  New  notes  in  elucidation 

of  the  Theory  of  the 
Winds. 

1757  Outline  and  Announcement 

of  a  course  of  Lectures 
on  Physical  Geography, 
with  a  brief  supplemen 
tary  consideration  of  the 
question  whether  the 
west  winds  in  our  locality 
are  moist  because  of  b.iv- 
ing  passed  over  a  broad 
stretch  of  sea 

1758  New  Scientific  Conception 

of  Motion  and  Rest. 

1759  Some  Tentative  Considera 

tions  of  Optimism. 
1759  Schiller  born. 
1762  Fichte  born 
1762  Publication    of    Rous 
seau's  Jzmile  and  Contrat 
social. 

1762  Die  falsche  Spitzfindig- 
keit  der  vicr  syllogisti- 
schen  /^iguren  ertviescn 
(The  Erroneous  Sophis 
try  of  the  Four  Syllogistic 
Figures  Demonstrated). 

1762  Der  eir.zig  mogliche  Be- 
weisgrund  zu  einer  De 
monstration  vom  Da- 
sein  Gottes  (The  Only 
Possible  Basis  of  a  Dem 
onstration  of  the  Exist 
ence  of  God). 

1762  Untersuchung  ilbcr  die 
Deutlichkcit  der  Grund- 
sdtze  der  natiirluhen 


Theologie  und  Moral 
(Researches  on  the  Dis 
tinctness  of  the  Princi 
ples  of  Natural  Theology 
and  Morals).  (Prcis- 
schnft  der  Berliner 
Akademie,  printed  in 
1764.) 

1763  1'ersuch,  den  Be  griff  der 

negativen     Grosscn     in 
die    II  eltzveisheit  einzu- 
fiihren   (Attempt  to  In 
troduce    the     Notion    of 
Negative  Quantities  into 
Philosophy). 
1763  F.  A.  Schultz  dies. 

1764  1'ersuch  iibcr  die  Krank- 

hciten  des  Koffes  (Essay 
on  the  Diseases  of  the 
Head  )  {R'onigsb.  Ztg.}. 

1764  Beobachtungen  tiber  das 

Gefiihl  des  Schonen  und 
F.rhabenen  (Observa 
tions  on  the  Feeling  of 
the  Beautiful  and  the 
Sublime). 

1765  Information  on    the   Plan 

of  his  Lectures. 

1766  Trdume    eines     Geister- 
sehers,   erldutert  durch 
TrciurAe  der  Metaphysik 
(Dreams  of  a  Spirit-Seer, 
etc.). 

1766  Gottsched  dies. 
1768  Von  dem  erst  en  Grunde 
des  Unterschieds  der 
G  eg  end  en  im  Ruum  (On 
the  Fundamental  Reason 
for  the  Difference  of  Lo 
calities  in  Space).  (A'ffn. 
Nachr. ) 


CHRONOLOGY. 


289 


1770  Kant  obtains  his  full  pro 
fessorship  in  logic  and 
metaphysics. 

1770  Disputatio  de  mundi  sen- 

sibilis     atque    inteliigi- 

bilisforma  et  principiis. 

1770  (Holbach)  Systeme  de 

la  nature. 

1775  Von    den    verschiedenen 
Racen      des      Menschen 
(Ankiindigung  der  I'or- 
lesungen  iibcr  physische 
Geograph  ie) .     (On     the 
Different  Races  of  Men.) 

1776  Ufber  das  Dessauer  Phi 

lanthropic.    (Kon.  Ztg.) 

1776  North  American  Dec 
laration  of  Independence. 

1776  Hume  dies. 

1778  Voltaire  dies. 

1778  Rousseau  dies. 

1780  Joseph  II.  ascends  the 
throne. 

1781  Lessing  dies. 

1781  Kritik  dcr  reinen  Ver- 
nunft  (Critique  of  Pure 
Reason. 

1783  Prolegomena     zu     einer 
jedcn    kiinftigen    Afeta- 
physik,   die  als  IVj'ssen- 
schaft    zvird    auflretcn 
konnen  (Prolegomena  to 
Every  Future  Metaphys 
ics,   etc.). 

'784  Idee  zu  einer  allgemeinen 
Gesch.  in  iveltbiirger- 
licher  Absicht  (Ideas  for 
a  Universal  History, etc.). 

1784  Beantuuortung  dcr  Frage 

Was    ist    Aufkldrung? 
(Both   the  preceding  ar 


ticles  in  the  Berliner 
Monatsschrift.) 

1785  Criticisms  of  Herder's 
Ideen  zur  Fhilos.  der 
Geschichte.  (Jenaische 
Litter  aturztg.) 

1785  Ueber  Vnlkane  im  Monde 
(On  Volcanoes  in  the 
Moon). 

1785  Von  der  Unrechtmassig- 
keit  dcs  Bilchernath- 
drucks  (On  the  Illegality 
of  Literary  Piracy). 

1785  Bestimmung  des  Be  griffs 
einer  AIenschenrace(D&- 
termination  of  the  Con 
cept  of  a  Race  of  Men). 

1785  Grundlcgung  zur  AJcla- 

physik  der  Sit  ten  (Foun 
dation  of  the  Metaphys 
ics  of  Morals). 

1786  Altitmasslictier     Anfavg 

der  RIenschengcschichle 
(Presumable  Origin  of 
Human  History).  (Berl 
Monatssckrift. ) 

1786  Was  heisst  sick  im  Pen- 
ken  orientieren  ?  (What 
is  the  Meaning  of  Orien 
tation  inThinking?)  (Ber 
liner  Afonatsschrift.) 

1786  Aletap hys ische  Anfangs- 
grttnde   der  Naturu'is- 
senschaften    (Metaphys 
ical    Rudiments    of    the 
Natural  Sciences). 
1786  Frederick    the    Great 
dies,    Frederick  William 
II.  ascends  the  throne. 
1788    Wollner's      religious 
edict. 


290 


CHRONOLOGY. 


1788  Ueber  den  Gebrauch  tcleo- 
logischer  Prinzipien  in 
der  Philosophic  (On  the 
Use  of  Teleological  Prin 
ciples  in  Philosophy). 
(Deutsch.  Aferk.). 

1788    Kritik    der  praktischen 
Vermmft     (Critique     of 
Practical  Reason). 
1789  French  Revolution. 

1790  Kritih  der  Urteilskraft 
(Critique  of  the  Judg 
ment). 

1790  Ueber  Philosophic  iiber- 
hat4.pt  (erste  Einl.  zur 
A'r.  d.  Urt.)  (On  Philos 
ophy  in  General). 

1790  Ueber  tine  Entdeckung, 
nach  der  alle  neue  Kri 
tik  der  reinen  I7 er  nun  ft 
durch  cine  dltere  ent- 
behrlich  gemacht  rver- 
den  soil  (On  a  Discovery 
by  which,  etc.).  (Against 
Eberhard). 

1790  Ueber  Schivarmerci  und 

die  Mittcl  dag  eg  en  (On 
Gushing  and  the  Means 
for  its  Prevention). 

1791  Ueber     das     Afisslingen 
aller  philos.  Versitchein 
der    Theodicee   (On    the 
Failure  of  all  Philosoph 
ical  Attempts  in  Theod 
icy).     (Berl.  A/on.) 

1792  Vom  radikalen  Bosen  (On 

the  Radically  Bad). 
(Berl.  Man  ) 

1792  The    continuation    of 
the  foregoing  articles  is 


prohibited  by  the  Berlin 
censorship. 

1793  Religion  innerhalb  der 
Crenzen  der  blossen  Ver 
nunft  (Religion  within 
the  Bounds  of  Mere  Rea 
son). 

1793  Ueber  den  Gemcinspruch . 

Das  mag  in  der  Theorie 
nchtig  sein,  tangt  aber 
nichtfUr  die  Praxis  (On 
the  Maxim :  Good  in 
Theory,  but  Bad  in  Prac 
tice).  (Berl.  Man.) 

1794  Etivas  tiber  den  Einfluss 

des  Monde  s  auf  die 
Witterung  (On  the  In 
fluence  of  the  Moon  on 
the  Weather).  (Berliner 
Mon.) 

1794  Pas  Endc  aller  Dinge 
(The  End  of  all  Things). 
(Berl.  Afon.) 

1794  Cabinet  order  of  the  King 

and    Kant's    promise    to 
write  nothing  more  on  re 
ligion. 
1795  Peace  of  Basel. 

1795  Zum  eTjjigen  Frieden  (On 

Universal  Peace). 

1796  Kant  discontinues  his  lec 

tures. 

1796  Von  einem  neuer dings  er- 
hobenen,  vornehmen  Ton 
in  der  Philosophic  (On  a 
Recent  Aristocratic  Tone 
in  Philosophy).  (Berl. 
Afon.} 

1796  Announcement  of  the  ap 
proaching  completion  of 


CHRONOLOGY. 


291 


a  tract  on  Universal 
Peace  in  Philosophy. 

1797  Metaphysische  Anfangs- 
grilnde  der  RechtsleJire 
(Metaphysical  Rudiments 
of  Jurisprudence). 

1797  Metaphysische  Anfangs- 
grilnde  der  Tugendlehre 
(Metaphysical  Rudiments 
of  Morals). 

1797  Ueber      ein      vcrmeintes 
Recht  aus  Mcnschenliebe 
zu  liigen  (On  a  Supposed 
Right  to  Lie  out  of  Love 
for  Man). 

1797  Frederick  William  II. 
dies  and  is  succeeded  by 
Frederick  William  III. 
WSllner  dismissed. 

1798  Ueber  die  Buchmacherei. 

Briefe  an  Fr   Ni- 


colai  (On  Bookmaking 
Two  Letters  to  Fr.  Nico- 
lai). 

1798  Der  Streit  der  Fakultdten 
(The  Battle  of  the  Facul 
ties). 

1798  Anthropologie  in  l>rag- 
matischer  llinsicht. 

1800  Logic,  edited  by  Jasche. 

1802  Physical  Geography,  ed 

ited  by  Rink. 

1803  Pedagogy,  edited  by  Rink. 

1804  On  the  Prize  Question  of 

the  Berlin  Academy : 
What  Real  Progress  has 
Metaphysics  made  inGer- 
many,  since  the  Times 
of  Leibnitz  and  Wolff? 
Edited  by  Rink. 
1804  Kant  dies  on  February  12. 


INDEX  TO  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


(Pages  1-163.) 


Accidents,  99. 

Actions  as  appearances  subject  to 
necessity,  113. 

Actuality,  66. 

Addition  and  arithmetic,  36. 

Air  is  elastic,  57-59- 

Alchemy,  140. 

Analogy,  cognition  by,  129. 

Analytical  and  synthetical,  14-15,  17, 
18,  22,  23,  25,  26,  27. 

Analytics  and  dialectics,  27. 

Anschauung  (visualisation),  17,  18,  at, 
30,  34,  120,  126,  140,  146 ;  and  mathe 
matics,  32. 

Antecedent,  53 ;  and  consequent,  72. 

Anthropomorphism, 128, 130;  avoided, 
13'. 

Antinomy,  105  et  seq.,  108. 

Apodeictic,  18,  33;  and  necessary,  35; 
and  a  priori,  144  ;  certainty  of  meta 
physics,  157. 

Appearance,  properties  of  a  body  be 
long  to,  44;  and  insufficiency,  126. 

Appearances,  space  the  form  of,  40; 
geometry  prescribes  to,  41 ;  objects 
are  mere,  42;  and  sensuous  per 
ception,  45;  and  things  in  them, 
selves,  75 ;  actions  as,  subject  to 
necessity,  113. 

Application  o  f  a  priori  to  experience, 
34- 

A  priori,  70;  knowledge  and  meta 
physics,  14;  and  synthetical,  15,26, 
29,  33  ;  judgment  (body  is  extended), 
16;  necessity,  16;  and  pure  mathe 
matics,  17,  32;  the  materials  of 
metaphysics,  23;  and  necessity,  28; 
at  the  bottom  of  metaphysics,  31  ; 
and  its  application  to  experience, 


34;  anticipating  actuality,  35;  at 
the  basis  of  the  empirical,  36  ;  apo- 
deictically  certain,  37;  intuition 
and  three  dimensions,  37;  is  it  a 
phantasm  ?  47;  things  not  cognised, 
50;  principles,  60;  rules,  64  ;  origin 
of  pure  concepts,  73  ;  basis  of  the 
possibility  of  laws,  80;  laws,  basis 
of  the  possibility  of  nature,  81; 
geometrical  laws,  83;  and  system; 
85;  understanding  determined,  137; 
concepts,  sources  of,  139;  definite 
and  compact,  141 ;  and  apodeicti- 
cal.  144;  transcendent  and  tran 
scendental,  150,  151;  missing  in 
Berkeley,  153. 

Aristotle,  86. 

Arithmetic  and  addition,  36. 

Association,  law  of,  4. 

Astrology,  140. 

Axioms,  60. 

Baumgarten,  19. 
Beattie,  5,  6. 

Beginning,  the  world  has  a,  105. 
Being,  a,  conceived  for  comprehend 
ing  the  connexion,  order,  and  unity 

of  the  world,  117. 
Beings  of  understanding,  na. 
Berkeley,  151,  152;  his  idealism,  49; 

a  priori  missing  in,  152;  dogmatic 

idealism  of,  153. 
Bodies,  primary  qualities  of,  43~44; 

mere  representations,  43. 
Body,  thing  in  itself,  as,  103. 
Boundary,  theology  (natural)  looks 

beyond,  134  ;  and  limits,  133. 
Bounds,  not  limits,  123;  and  limits 

125;  of  pure  reason,  120,  124. 


294 


INDEX  TO  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


Categories,  86,  87,  88,  89,  90,  105 ;  of 
deeper  meaning,  76;  and  under 
standing,  92;  and  logical  functions, 
94- 

Causality,  22;  and  succession,  in. 

Cause,  4,  53,  98  ;  a  pure  concept  of 
the  understanding,  58;  is  super- 
added,  59;.  and  effect,  66;  of  con 
nexions  in  the  world,  131. 

Challenge,  144. 

Challenging  the  critic,  157. 

Chimeras,  75. 

Chisels  and  engraver's  needle,  6-7. 

Circle,  law  of  the.  82. 

Cognition,  45  ;  of  the  understanding, 
93;  analogy,  129;  insufficiency  of 
the,  136. 

Common  sense,  6,  27,  29,  145;  no  right 
to  judge  in  metaphysics,  7;  appeal 
to,  144;  and  metaphysics,  146. 

Community,  66. 

Composite;  everything  is,  106. 

Concepts,  of  reason,  95 ;  having  their 
origin  in  reason,  118. 

Conflict  of  reason,  116. 

Congruent,  the  two  hands  not,  39, 

Connexions  in  the  world,  cause  of, 
131. 

Consciousness,  subject  of,  103. 

Consequent  and  antecedent,  72. 

Construction  and  experience,  146. 

Contradiction,  law  of,  16,  22,  27;  and 
synthetical  judgments,  15. 

Contrast  of  right  and  left,  39. 

Cosmological  idea.  104,  105. 

Crazy-quilt  of  metaphysics,  154. 

Criteria  of  truth,  universal  and  nec 
essary  laws,  152. 

Criterion  of  truth,  103. 

Critical  idealism,  49,  153. 

Critical  question,  24. 

Criticism,  standard  given  by,  163; 
and  metaphysics,  162. 

Critique,  contains  plan  of  metaphys 
ics,  139 ;  justified,  158 ;  whoever 
has  once  tasted,  etc..  140. 

Crusius's  compromise,  81. 

Degree,  66,  68. 

Descartes,  48;  his  sceptical  idealism. 


Determinability  and  necessity,  1x4 
Dialectics  an-i  analytics,  27. 
Difieience  of  equal  figures,  38-39. 
Diffuseness  of  the  plan,  8. 
Dogmatics,  downfall  of,  141. 
Dogmatic  slumber,  Kant's,  7. 
Dogmatic  twaddle,  140. 
Dogmatism  and  scepticism,  24,  138. 
Dreaming  idealism,  49. 

Effect  and  cause,  66. 

Effect  happens  in  time,  in. 

Ego,  100,  103. 

Eleatic  school,  151. 

Empirical  idealism,  48. 

Empirical  intuition,  33. 

Empirical  judgments,  16,  54,  55. 

Engraver's  needle,  chisels  and,  6-7. 

Equal  figures,  difference  of,  38-39. 

Experience,  16,  57,  58,  63;  geometry 
holds  all  possible,  46;  illusion  in 
transgressing.  48;  and  things  in 
themselves,  51;  objects  of  pos 
sible,  53 ;  judgments  of,  54,  55,  57. 
62,63;  possibility  of,  60;  intuitions 
and  judgments,  62;  understanding 
makes  it  possible,  84 ;  analogy  of, 
101 ;  and  the  real,  102;  things  in 
themselves  the  basis  of,  124,  and 
construction,  146;  truth  in,  151. 

Facility  of  solution,  28. 

Faculty  of  beginning   from  itself, 
freedom  a,  112-115. 

Fiction,  previous  to  our  acquaint 
ance,  space  would  be  mere,  41. 

Foam,  metaphysics  like,  21. 

Formal,  104. 

Form,  of  intuition,  a  priori,  35  ;  of 
sensibility,  pure  intuition  a,  36; 
without  perception  remains,  127. 

Four  ideas  of  reason,  107. 

Freedom,  114;  and  nature,  106.  a 
faculty  of  beginning  from  itself, 
112-115;  and  reason,  113;  rescued, 
practical,  114;  natural  necessity 
and,  115. 

Functions  of  the  understanding,  60. 

Fundamental  principles,  64. 

Geometry,  and  space,  36;  necessarily 
valid  of  space,  40 :  objects  coincide 


INDEX  TO  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


295 


with,  41 ;  prescribes  to  appear 
ances,  41  ;  holds  all  possible  expe 
rience,  46. 

Geometrical  laws,  83. 

Geometrical  sources,  83. 

Cetetzmussigkeit,  52. 

God.     (See  Bf inf.) 

Gothaische  gelehrte  Zritung,  156. 

Gottingensche  gelehrten  Ameigen,  149. 

Hand,  right  and  left,  39,40. 

Helices,  symmetric,  40. 

History  of  philosophy,  i. 

Horace,  3,  27. 

Hume,  David,  3,  4  6,  7,  10,  19,  21,  28, 
71,121,127,  130,  132;  his  problem, 
5,  8,  73;  his  spark  of  light,  7;  his 
doubts,  9,  70 

Hyperphysical,  52. 

Idealism,  44,  150,  151;  Kant's,  43-44  ; 
charges  of,  48  ;  empirical,  48  ;  tran 
scendental,  48,  49;  critical,  49,  153  ; 
dreaming,  49;  of  Berkeley,  49,  153  ; 
visionary,  49;  Cartesian  or  mate 
rial,  103,  104;  mystical,  152;  of 
Descartes,  sceptical,  153. 

Ideality  of  space  and  time,  47.    - 

Idea  of  unity  system,  119. 

Id»  as,  reason  the  source  of,  92  ;  theo 
logical,  117;  transcendental,  their 
origin  In  reason,  118,  137. 

Illusion  and  truth,  152. 

Illusion  in  transgressing  experience, 
48. 

Illusory  metaphysics,  139. 

Imagination,  78. 

Immaterial  being,  125. 

Ii  cidental  and  necessary,  106. 

Incomprehensibility,  118;  of  causal* 
ity,  70. 

Infinite,  the  world  is,  106. 

Infinite  number  of  parts,  no. 

!muffic:ency  and  appearance,  126. 

Intelligence,  supreme,  137. 

Intelligible  world.  77. 

Intern  ,1  constitution  of  things  never 
revealed,  123. 

Internal  sense  and  soul,  104. 

It  tuit  d,  everything  as  it  appears,  38. 

lutuite,  how  to,  a  priori,  34. 


Intuition,  33.  35,  37 ;  at  the  founda 
tion  of  mathematics,  35,  38;  a  pri 
ori,  and  three  dimensions,  37;  space 
the  form  of  the  external,  40;  ob 
jects  given  in,  42;  of  space  and 
time,  appearance,  48  ;  none  beyond 
sensibility,  77;  universal  form  of, 
84. 

Intuitive,  33. 

Judgment  denned,  63  ;  empirical,  54 
55  ;  of  experience,  54.  55,  57,  62,  63; 
of  perception,  55,  57;  synthetical 
59  ;  two  sorts,  148. 

Kant's  dogmatic  slumber,  7. 

Labor  of  research,  28. 

Law,  conformity  to,  52  et  seq.,  103; 
of  the  circle,  82 ;  reason  prescribes 
the,  118;  reason's  production,  118. 

Laws,  subjective,  53  ;  of  nature,  their 
sources,  54;  universal,  54;  of  na 
ture,  particular  and  universal,  81; 
of  nature,  not  in  space,  83  ;  univer 
sal  and  necessary,  criteria  of  truth, 
152- 

Legislation  of  nature  in  ourselves, 
80. 

Legislative,  the  a.  priori  is, 

Leibnitz,  3. 

Limits,  not  bounds,  123;  contain  ne 
gations,  125  ;  and  bounds,  125  ;  and 
boundary,  133. 

Locke,  3,  19.  43. 

Logical  functions  and  categories,  94. 

Logical  table,  61. 

Longwindedness  of  the  work,  10. 

Materialism,  rash  assertions  destroy, 

137- 

Mathematical  judgments,  16. 

Mathematicians  were  philosophers, 
41- 

Mathematics,  nature  of  33;  a  priori, 
32;  and  Anschauung,  32;  and  vis 
ual  form,  32;  how  possible,  32  et 
seq.;  intuitions  at  the  foundation 
°f  35.  38;  applied  to  nature,  69; 
must  be  referred  to  appearances, 
73;  and  metai>h)sics,  91. 


296 


INDEX  TO  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


Maxims,  114. 

Mental  space  renders  physical  space 
possible,  42. 

Metaphysicians,  oratory  of,  29  ;  sus 
pended,  29. 

Metaphysics,  135  ;  whether  possible, 
1-3.  20,  24  ;  impossible  according  to 
Hume,  4;  not  every  one  is  bound 
to  study,  ii  ;  must  satisfy  the  de 
mands,  12;  knowledge  of,  lying  be 
yond  experience,  13  ;  and  a  priori 
knowledge,  14;  sources  of,  13  14; 
like  foam,  21 ;  the  materials  of,  a 
priori,  23  ;  and  synthetical  proposi 
tions,  24  ;  and  synthetic  a  priori 
propositions,  26-C7;  difficulty  of,  28; 
and  transcendental  philosophy,  30; 
a  priori  at  the  bottom  of,  31  ;  as  a 
science,  31,  147;  young  thinkers 
partial  to,  78;  and  mathematics,  91; 
how  possible?  91;  grounds  of,  138; 
critique  contains  plan  of,  139  ;  illu 
sory,  139;  of  decay,  141;  will  never 
be  given  up,  142;  and  common 
sense,  146;  crazy-quilt  of,  154;  as 
sertions  of,  world  tired  of,  155; 
standard  of,  156;  apodeictic  cer 
tainty  of,  157;  and  criticism,  162. 

Nature,  defined,  50,  52,  54;  science  of, 
precedes  physics,  51,  65;  sources  of 
its  laws,  54 ;  system  of,  64 ;  its  uni 
versal  laws  cognised  a  priori,  64; 
mathematics  applied  to,  69 ;  how 
possible,  79;  the  totality  of  rules, 
79;  legislation  of,  in  ourselves,  80; 
a  priori  laws  basis  of  the  possibil 
ity  of,  81;  laws  of,  particular  and 
universal  81;  its  laws  not  in  space, 
83  ;  and  freedom,  106. 

Necessary,  62;  and  apodeictic,  35; 
universality  and  objective  validity, 
56;  and  incidental,  106, 

Necessary  Being,  116. 

Necessity,  67 ;  of  habit,  4  ;  (according 
to  Hume)  a  long  habit,  28  ;  and  a 
priori,  28  ;  actions  as  appearances 
subject  to,  113;  and  determinabil- 
ity,  114;  natural,  and  freedom,  115; 
unconditional,  136. 


Noumena,  (things  in  themselves).  72 
76,  97;  and  creations  of  tlie  under 
standing,  75  ;  as  the  void,  125. 

Objective,  55  et  seq. 

Objective  validity  and  necessary  uni 
versality,  56. 

Objects,  coincide  with  geometry,  41; 
are  mere  appearances,  42;  given  in 
intuition,  42;  of  possible  experi 
ence,  53;  and  things  in  themselves 
in  ;  unknown,  56. 

Obscurity,  12. 

Ontology,  90. 

Oratory  of  metaphysicians,  29. 

Oswald,  5. 

Ought  and  reason,  113. 

Particularia,  60. 

Perception,  judgments  of,  55,  57. 

Permanence  of  substances,   loi-ioa 

Phantasm,  is  the  a  priori  a?  47. 

Phenomena,  subjective  basis  of,  42; 
in  space,  102. 

Philosophers,  mathematicians  were 
41. 

Philosophy,  history  of,  i. 

Physical  space,  mental  space  renders 
it  possible.  42. 

Physics,  preceded  by  Science  of  Na 
ture,  51. 

Physiological  table,  61. 

Plan  of  the  work,  analytical,  u. 

Platner,  118. 

Plurativa  judicia^  60. 

Popular,  I  might  have  made  my  ex 
position,  10. 

Popularity  and  Prolegomena,  8-9. 

Possibility,  66. 

Practical  freedom  rescued,  114. 

Predicables,  87. 

Predicates,  99;  belonging  to  appear 
ance,  43. 

Priestley,  5. 

Primary  qualities  of  bodies,  43-44. 

Prolegomena,  for  teachers,  i ;  and 
popularity,  8-9;  analytical,  25;  prep 
aratory,  25  ;  as  an  outline,  159. 

Properties  of  a  body  belong  to  ap 
pearance,  44. 


INDEX  TO  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


297 


Property,  similarity  of  sensation  to, 
44. 

Pseudo-science,  140. 

Pure  concepts,  of  the  understanding, 
60,  63,  64  ;  table  of  the,  61  ;  a  priori 
origin  of,  73  ;  of  reason,  93. 

Pure  intuition,  33;  a  form  of  sensi 
bility,  36. 

Pure  reason,  94,  97. 

Quantity,  65,  68  ;  and  things  in  them 
selves,  67  ;  of  the  world,  109. 
Questions,  four,  31. 

Real  and  experience,  the,  102. 

Reason,  the  source  of  ideas,  92 ;  and 
understanding,  92;  pure  concepts 
of,  93,  94,  95.  97;  divided  with  it 
self,  107;  four  ideas  of,  107;  and 
freedom,  113;  and  ought,  113;  con 
flict  of,  116;  concepts  having  their 
origin  in,  118;  prescribes  the  law, 
118;  at  variance  with  itself,  119; 
bounds  of  pure,  120,  124,  128;  finds 
no  satisfaction  in  itself, 124;  teaches 
nothing  concerning  the  thing  in  it 
self  134  ;  freed  by  the  theological 
idea,  136. 

Red  and  vermillion,  44. 

Reid,  5. 

Rules,  64  ;  a  priori,  64. 

Scepticism,  21,  121;  and  dogmatism, 
24. 

Science  of  nature,  65. 

Scholia,  138,  139  et  seq. 

Self,  the  thinking,  ino. 

Sensation,  similarity  of,  to  property, 
44- 

Senses,  business  of  the,  62. 

Sensibility,  form  of,  and  a  priori,  35; 
time  and  space  conditions  of  our, 
37;  no  intuition  beyond,  77. 

Sensible  world  no  sham.  44. 

Sensuous  perception   and  appear 
ances,  45. 

Similarity  of  sensation  to  property, 
44. 

Simple  and  composite,  106. 

Skepticism  and  dogmatism,  132. 

Solution,  facility  of,  28. 


Soul,  96,  100;  as  a  substance,  101,  102 
105  ;  and  internal  sense.  104  ;  the 
nature  of,  121,  136;  vacuity  in  the, 
160. 

Sources  of  a  priori  concepts,  139. 

Space,  122;  and  Time,  35;  and  geom 
etry,  36 ;  and  time  conditions  of 
our  sensibility,  37;  three  dimen 
sions,  37;  and  time,  mere  form>, 
38;  and  time  presupposed,  38 ;  the 
form  of  appearances,  40;  thj  form 
of  the  external  intuition,  40;  would 
be  mere  fiction  previous  to  our  ac 
quaintance,  41  ;  mental  renders 
physical  possible,  42;  aud  time  and 
things  in  themselves,  47;  and  time, 
ideality  of,  47;  aud  time,  intuitions 
of,  appearance,  48;  not  a  store  of 
laws,  84 ;  phenomena  in,  xoz ;  and 
time  belong  to  appearances,  152. 

Spark  of  light,  Hume's  7. 

Standard  given  by  criticism,  163. 

Subjective  basis  of  phenomena,  42. 

Subjective  laws,  53. 

Subsistence,  70. 

Substance,  66,  98,  TOO;  of  things,  99; 
permanence  of,  101-102;  soul  as  a, 
101,  102,  105. 

Succession,  66,  72 ;  and  causality,  in. 

Sufficient  reason,  never  been  proved, 
143- 

Sun,  shining  on  stone,  59,  63 ;  the 
cause  of  heat,  72. 

Superadded,  cause  is,  59. 

Supreme  Being,  96,  125,  126,  127,  129, 
130,  131. 

Supreme  Cause,  131,  132. 

Supreme  intelligence,  137. 

Supreme  Reason,  132. 

Symmetric  helices,  40. 

Synthetical,  and  analytical,  14-15,  18, 
22,  23,  25,  26,  27;  t,nd  a  priori,  15 
26,  29.  33;  Judgments  and  the  law 
of  Contradiction  15,  59;  of  7  +  5 
=  12,  17  ;  propositions  and  meta 
physics,  24. 

System,  of  nature,  64;  and  a  priori 
85  ;  idea  of  unity,  119. 

Teachers,  Prolegomena  for,  i. 
Test,  157,  161. 


298 


INDEX  TO  KANT'S  PROLEGOMENA. 


Theological  idea,  117;  reason  freed 
by  the,  136. 

Theology  (natural)  looks  beyond  the 
boundary,  134. 

Thing  in  itself,  as  body,  103;  reason 
teaches  nothing  concerning,  134. 

Things  in  themselves,  53,  70,  120,  121, 
122;  and  space  and  time,  47;  cog 
nition  of  impossible,  50;  under 
standing  must  conform  to,  50;  and 
experience,  51;  and  quantity,  67; 
(noumena),  72,  76;  serve  to  deci 
pher  appearances,  73  ;  and  appear 
ances,  75;  and  objects,  in;  the 
basis  of  experience,  124. 

Things,  unknown  in  themselves,  43; 
substance  of,  99 ;  never  revealed, 
internal  constitution  of,  123. 

Thinking  de6ned,  62, 

Thinking  self,  the,  100. 

Time  and  Space,  35;  conditions  of 
our  sensibility,  37;  mere  forms,  38; 
presupposed,  38 ;  belong  to  appear 
ances,  152. 

Transcendent,  92,  104;  transcenden 
tal,  a  priori  aud,  150,  151. 

Transcendental,  philosophy  and  met 
aphysics,  30;  problem,  32  et  seq.; 
idealism,  48,  49;  philosophy,  sys 
tem  of,  87;  ideas,  their  origin  in 
reason,  118;  a  priori  and  tran 
scendent,  150,  151. 

Truth,  and  dreaming,  45 ;  criterion 
of,  103,  149  ;  in  experience,  151 ;  and 
illusion,  152. 


Understanding,  must  conform  to 
things  in  themselves,  50;  functions 
of  the,  60;  pure  concepts  of  the, 
60.  63;  table  of  the  pure  concepts 
of  the,  6r  ;  business  of  the,  62  ;  crea 
tions  of.  and  noumena,  75;  vaga 
ries  of  the,  78  ;  constitution  of  our 
79;  prescribes  laws  to  nature,  82; 
laws  inhere  in  the,  83;  makes  ex 
perience  possible,  84;  and  cate 
gories,  92;  and  reason,  92;  cogni 
tions  of  the,  93;  beings  of,  112; 
world  of,  125  ;  systematic  unity  be 
longs  to,  138. 

Unity  a  mode  of  cognition,  119. 

Universality,  necessary,  55. 

Universal  laws,  54  ;  laws  of  nature, 
cognised  a  priori,  64. 

Universal  validity,  69. 

Universally  valid,  62. 

Vacuity  in  the  soul,  160. 
Vagaries  of  the  understanding,  78. 
Virgil,  12. 

Visionary  idealism,  49. 
Visual  form  and  mathematics,  32. 
Visualisation   (Ansrkauung)     18.  21. 
Void,  the,  that  of  which  we  can  know 
nothing,  125. 


'ung,  66. 
Wisdom  incarnate,  2. 
Wolf,  19. 

World,  128;  questions  of  its  duration 
and  quantity,  122. 


INDEX   TO   THE  ARTICLE   ON   KANT'S  PHI- 
LOSOPHY. 


(Pages  167-240.) 


Acvaghosha,  228. 

After-imate,  224. 

Agnosticism,  237. 

Amitabha,  228. 

Anschauung,  184,  187. 

Antinomies,  221,  237;  Kant's,  195   et 

seq.;  not  true  antinomies,  197. 
A  poster iori  and  a  priori,  181,  182. 
Appearance,  two  meanings  of.  232; 

time  and  space  appertain  to,  231, 

232. 
A  priori,  198;  not  innate,  181;  and  a. 

posteriori,  181,  182;  purely  formal, 

207;  has  objective  value,  214. 
Apriority,  general  applicability,  226. 
Aristotle,  169,  178. 
Arfipa,  228. 
Asceticism,  211. 

Berkeley,  177;  his  idealism,  175;  his 
philosophy,  199;  and  Kant,  210. 

Cartesian  syllogism,  the,  169. 
Categories  and  modes  of  existence, 

219. 

Causation,  200  et  spq. 
Cat-se  and  reason,  201  et  seq. 
Christ   212. 
Clifford,  216;  on  the  thing  in  itself, 

237- 

Clusters,  things  are,  217. 
Color-blind,  228. 
Confucius,  212. 
Constructions  and  mathematical 

theorems.  215. 
Construction,  world  of  senses  is  a, 


Cosmos,  221  et  seq. 
Critique  of  Pure  Reason^  175. 

Datein  and  Sefn,  227. 
Delphic  maxim,  168. 
Descartes,  169. 
Dictates  of  our  mind,  207. 
Divisibility  of  line,  infinite,  216, 
Dogmatism,  172. 

Edmunds,  Albert  J.,  188,  189,  iga. 
Ego,  metaphysical,  170. 
Empirical,  180. 
Extension,  225. 

Feder,  175. 

Flux  of  things.  218. 

Formal,  and  the  sensory,  the,  ao8 
constructed,  the  purely,  215. 

Formal   cognition   the   key   to    mys 
teries,  227. 

Formal   knowledge  gives    system, 
purely,  226. 

Formal  sciences,  the  organ  of  cogni 
tion,  212. 

Formal  theorems,  general,  207. 

Form  both  subjective  and  objective, 
212  et  seq. 

Garve,  175. 

Generalisations,  origin  of,  219. 

God,  178,  221  et  seq.,  228;  the  world- 
order,  239. 

God  problem,  237  et  seq. 

Golden  Rule,  212. 

GSttingtHtche    GeUkrten  Anztigen, 
175- 


3°o 


INDEX  TO  "KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 


Heine,  Heinrich,  173. 
Hom;iloidal,  233. 

Hume,  171 ;  his  problem,  198,  199,  200 
et  seq. 

Ideal  and  subjective,  206,  214. 
Idealism  and  realism,  222-223. 
Ideality,  of  space  and  time,  187;  not 

subjectivity,  204  et  seq. 
Image,  184  ;  after-,  224. 
Infinite  divisibility  of  line,  216. 
Innate  ideas.  182,  200, 
Innate  not  a  priori,  181. 
Intuition,  184. 
Inventor  a  finder,  the,  220. 

Jacobi,  223. 

Kant,  his  philosophical  reform,  171; 
his  personal  traits.  173  ;  his  indig 
nation,  177 ;  his  terms,  178;  on  meta 
physics,  178-179,  195;  on  reality, 187; 
and  Swedenborg,  188  et  seq  ;  his 
antinomies,  195  et  seq.;  his  prob 
lem,  198;  puzzled  by  the  a  priori, 
203  et  seq.;  and  Berkeley,  210  ;  his 
conception  of  morality,  211  ;  on 
space  and  time,  231  ;  his  definition 
of  things  in  theinselves,  235. 

Kantism,  moral  aspect  of,  210  et  seq. 

Lao-Tze,  212,  228. 
Laws,  218. 

Leibnitz,  189,  190,  195. 
Lichtenberg,  170. 
Locke,  171,  200. 
Logos,  228. 

Mach.  Ernst,  233. 

Mathematical   theorems   and  con 
structions,  215. 

Measure  of  motion  (Time),  216. 

Mental  construction   and   straight 
line,  234. 

Metaphysics,  178;  the  old,  172;  Kant 
on  178-179,  195  ;  sources  of,  179. 

Mind  dictates,  our,  207. 

Mind,  like  the  spider's  thread.  206. 

Modes  of  existence  and  categories, 
219. 


Morality,  Kant's  conception  of,  211. 
Mundus  intelligibilis,  179,  228. 

Naturalists  of  Greece,  167. 

Nature,  uniformities  of,  205. 

Neumann,  196. 

Nirvana,  228. 

Nomenclature  is  arbitrary,  222. 

Norms  of  superreal,  227  et  seq. 

Noumena,   228  et    seq.;    represents 

things,  229. 
Noumenon,   and    phenomenon,    180- 

181  ;  space-conception  a,  234. 

Objectified,  every  sentient  subject, 
230;  subject,  the,  225,  226,  231. 

Objective  and  subjective,  216,  217. 

Objectivity  of  space  and  time,  230  et 
seq. 

Objects,  what  are  they  ?  224. 

Organ  of  cognition,  formal  sciences 
the,  212. 

Paulsen,  173,  176,  177. 

Phenomenon  and  noumenon,  180-181 

Philosophy,  Jove   of  wisdom,  168; 

practical,  167. 

Photographer's  camera,  184. 
Physiological  space,  233. 
Plato,  236. 

Prolegomena,  177,  202  et  seq. 
Pure,  182. 

Real,  224. 

Realism  and  idealism,  222-223. 

Real  time  and  space,  229. 

Reason,  and  cause,  201  et  seq.;  and 

understanding,  180. 
Red  and  vermillion,  209  et  seq. 
Religion,  the  sensory  in,  211. 

Scholasticism,  168-169. 
Schopenhauer,  197,  223,  236  ;  his  Will, 

237. 

Sein  and  Daiein,  227. 
Self-perception,  224. 
Sensations,  subjective,  228. 
Senses,  world  of,  a  construction,  234. 
Sensory,  the  formal  and  the,  208;  in 

religion,  the,  211. 
Sewall,  Frank,  189. 


INDEX  TO  "KANT'S  PHILOSOPHY. 


301 


Socrates,  168. 

Sophists,  the,  168. 

Soul,  221  et  seq.;  Swedenborg  on  the, 
193- 

Space  and  time,  not  objects,  187; 
ideality  of,  187;  objectivity  of,  225, 
226,  230  et  seq  ;  real,  229;  forms  of 
any  existence,  131;  Kant  on,  231; 
appertain  to  appearances,  231,  232. 

Space-conception,  and  space,  233;  a 
noumenon,  234. 

Space,  physiological,  233  ;  and  space- 
conception,  233. 

Spider's  thread,  mind  like  the,  206. 

Spinoza,  179. 

Straight  line  and  mental  construc 
tion,  234. 

Subject,  229;  representation  of  the, 
224;  in  itself  empty,  225;  the  ob 
jectified,  226;  objectified,  every 
sentient,  230,  231. 

Subjective,  and  ideal,  206,214;  and 
objective,  216,  217. 

Subjectivity,  not  ideality,  204  et  seq.; 
science  eliminates,  235. 

Succession,  217,  225. 

Suchness,  208  et  seq. 

Superreal.  norms  of,  227  et  seq. 

Swedenhorg,  Emanuel,  170,  228;  and 
Kant,  188  et  seq.;  on  the  soul,  193. 

Terms,  Kant's,  178. 

Theology,  178. 

Thing  in  itself,  Clifford  on  the,  237. 


Things   in   themselves,   234   et    seq.; 

Kant's  definition  of,  235  ;  a.  vagary 

236. 
Things,    represented    by    noumena 

229  :  are  clusters,  217  ;  flux  of,  218; 
and  unities,  221. 

Thisness,  208  et  seq. 
Tilly,  Frank,  175. 

Time  and  space,  ideality  of,  187;  not 
objects,  187;   objectivity  of  225,226, 

230  et  seq.;  real,  229;  appertain  to 
appearances,  231,  232;  forms  of  any 
existence,  231  ;  Kant  on,  231. 

Time  (measure  of  motion),  216. 
Transcendental,  182;   and  transcend 

ent,  183. 
Transcendent  and  transcendental, 

183. 

Tufts,  James  H.,  173. 
Twaddle,  dogmatical,  172. 
Twice  two,  not  one,  218. 

Understanding  and  reason,  180. 
Uniformities,  218;  of  nature,  205. 
Unities  and  things,  221. 

Vaihinger,  i8g. 

Vermillion  and  red,  209  et  seq. 

Watts,  James,  220. 
Weber,  Prof.  A.,  175. 
Windelband,  173. 
Wolf,  170. 

Zeno,  216. 


KANT,  I. 


Prolegomena  to  any  future        3 
metajhysics.