Skip to main content

Full text of "Lectures on theoretical ethics: notes taken in the class-room of Dr. Hamilton"

See other formats


P  435 
331 


Dniversit^  Library, 
OCT    29  1 89b 

•    PRINCETON,  N.  J. 


^ 


-..J 


&tbt*arn  trf 


-|l6ub  X?"wmc| 


• 


LECTURES 


rn 


HEORETICKL   bXHICS, 


NOTES 


TAKEN   IN  THE  CLASS-ROOM  OF 


Dr.. Hamilton. 


•A 


TRRNTON,  N.  J.: 
MacCbp.llihh  .t  Quiai.r.Y,  Printers,  16  Bast  State  Stbeet. 

1883. 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2010  with  funding  from 

Princeton  Theological  Seminary  Library 


http://www.archive.org/details/lecturesontheoreOOhami 


LECTURES 


rn 


1 HEORETICUL  MHICS, 


NOTES 


TAKEN  IN  THE  CLASS-ROOM   OF 

Dr.  Himilton. 


-TilENTON,  N.  J.: 
MacCbellish  &  QtJioLET,  Book  and  Job  Pbintebr,  1G  East  State  Stbbst. 

1883. 


THEORETICAL  ETHICS. 


LECTURE  I. 


THEORETICAL  ETHICS  is  a  difficult  branch  and  can  be 
mastered  only  by  attentive  study.  Practical  ethics  per- 
tains to  those  moral  laws  which  are  very  commonly  known 
and  appreciated  by  all  mankind.  But  great  difficulties 
arise  when  we  attempt  to  give  reasons  for  these  common 
modes  of  action,  because  we  enter  a  metaphysical  realm. 
We  must  go  out  of  ourselves  and  look  at  our  own  lives  and 
actions,  making  two  beings,  as  it  were,  of  one.  In  Ethics, 
man,  as  the  creature  and  doer  of  duty,  looks  at  himself  in 
the  light  of  God's  law.  He  becomes,  as  it  were,  three 
beings:  (1)  The  moral  agent;  (2)  moral  agent,  looking  at  him- 
self; (3)  a  philosophical  agent,  looking  from  above  over  all. 
While  it  is  difficult,  we  can  make  some  progress  and  can  dis- 
prove Sidney  Smith's  saying:  "All  metaphysical  studies  are 
absurd,  and  its  students  are  like  men  who  try  to  look  down 
their  own  throat  by  aid  of  a  lighted  candle." 

I.  DEFINITION  OF  THE  SCIENCE  NECESSARY. 

[1)  Wcmust  sjjecialize  field  of  study.  Aristotle,  in  his  Nico- 
machean  Ethics,  made  his  sphere  too  large.  Aristotle  said 
the  end  of  practical  wisdom  was  happiness.  The  perfect 
man  chose  a  meayi  in  everything  and  avoided  extremes. 
This  is  too  general,  and  shows  that  among  the  Greeks  the 
moral  sense  was  not  very  strong. 

(^)  For  avoidance  of  obscurity  and  confusion.  The  scholastic 
theologians  made  a  mistake  in  not  separating  ethics  from 
theology.  Some  Scotch  writers  go  over  the  whole  of  human 
nature,  all  of  which  is  indeed  concerned  in  duty,  but  in 


101240 


reading  their  works  we  find  great  difficulty  to  know  in  what 
way  some  of  their  discussions  bear  upon  Ethics. 

[3)  For  rejection  of  error.  Any  system  which  does  not  in- 
clude and  account  for  all  Ethical  phenomena  is  incomplete 
and  useless. 

II.  VARIOUSLY  DEFINED. 

Ethics  according  to — 

Birks,=;S'cfewce  of  Ideal  Humanity. 
Waylaiid,^/Sc^e?i<?e  of  Moral  Law. 
Bascoraj^^Sczmce  of  Duty. 
Whewell,=^czenee  of  Rights  and  Obligations. 
Calderwood,=^c?ence    of    Moral    Actions.,   of    Moral 
Natures  and  Moral  Relations. 

III.  HAMILTON— SCIENCE  OF  MORAL  LIFE. 


(/)  Science.  Exact,  complete  and  systematic  knowledge 
and  laws  of  any  department  of  existence.  Science  is  not  any 
more  true  than  ordinary  knowledge. 

{2)  Life.  This  word  has  not  a  distinct  meaning  in  modern 
languages.  We  might  define  :  Life,  the  possession  and  ex- 
ercise of  a  certain  kind  or  class  of  powers.  We  divide  life 
into — [a)  Organic  and  (6)  Psychical.  The  Organic  again 
divides  into  animal  and  vegetable  life.  Thus  we  have  three 
ideas  under  the  one  word. 

The  Greeks  had  three  words  :  /S'lo^-,  fitoTf)^ :  Latin,  vita,  life 
of  man,  his  rational  life.  Zojv] :  applied  to  animal  life,  cor- 
poreal. <puio  {(poTov.,  plant,)  life  of  a  plant.  Latin,  fui;  Eng- 
lish, to  be. 

These  three  kinds  of  life  were  granted  three  words 
in  ancient  languages,  but  not  in  our  English  tongue. 
There  is  a  community  of  nature  between  vegetable  and 
animal  life,  but  psychical  life  differs  from  both. 

[S)  Moral  Life. — Man's  life  as  rational,  may  be  considered 
in  different  ways.  We  speak  of  his  "individual,"  "social," 
"  political,"  "  domestic"  and  "  religious  "  life. 


Moral  life. — The  rational  life  of  man,  so  far  as  it  results 
from  the  consideration  and  perception  of  the  distinction 
between  right  and  wrong. 

IV.  REAL  DEFINITION. 

(1)  This  is  a  real  definition  and  not  a  nominal  one,  and  in 
this  lies  its  importance  and  value.  The  distinction  between 
"real "  and  "nominal "  comes  from  the  Schoolmen,  and  has 
been  noticed  by  many. 

Whaieley.  "W.  says,  the  '^nominal"  explains  the  idea  of 
a  thing  and  the  ^^real"  explains  the  thing  itself.  Answer: 
But  we  explain  a  thing  and  also  the  idea;  we  cannot 
separate  "real"  and  "nominal"  in  this  way. 

Locke  explained  "real"  and  "nominal"  in  connection 
with  his  two  essences.  "Nominal"  essence,  that  of  which 
we  have  a  conception;  the  name  of  a  thing  expresses  its 
nominal  essence.  But  he  says  in  all  substantial  essences 
there  are  many  things  about  which  we  know  nothing.  In 
a  "  nominal"  definition  we  have  only  a  part  of  the  essence, 
while  in  a  "  real "  we  have  the  whole  thing  as  known  to 
the  mind  of  God. 

Mill.  Every  true  definition,  whatever  it  may  be  of,  may 
be  viewed  in  two  lights — 

1.  Analytic,  explanatory,  giving  us  clear  understanding 
of  some  word  or  idea,  nominal. 

2.  Along  with  the  nominal  there  may  be  other  defini- 
tions which  not  only  explain  the  nature  of  a  thing,  but  make 
us  feel  that  there  are  real  things,  to  which  the  "nominal" 
definitions  refer. 

{2)  Moral  beings  and  their  lives  are  real  things. 

[3]  Tests  for  results. — Our  definition  being  "real,"  it  will 
furnish  such  a  te^t.  Any  theory  which  lands  us  in  doctrines 
without  any  morals  is  false.  Every  investigation  must 
square  its  results  with  the  teachings  of  common  sense. 


6 
V.  VALUE  OF  ETHICAL  STUDIES. 

(1)  They  exhibit  to  us  the  jiigh£stJorra^of_life  and  being. 
(2)  Call  for  the  keenest  exercise  of.  mtellect.  (3)  Aid  to  a 
right  determination  of  one's  personal  life.  (4)  Prepare  for  a 
satisfactory  "uiiderstanding  of  the  most  important  sciences. 
Ethics,  the  highest  plane  of  purely  human  thought. 


LECTURE  II. 

Problems,  Methods,  Theories. 

L  Theoretical  Ethics,  philosophy  of  moral  life. 
II.  Method  Necessary. 
III.  Three  General  Theories. 

(1)  Egoism.     (2)  Utilitarianism.     (3)  Intuitionism. 

I.  Being  the  philosophy  of  moral  life,  it  treats  four  classes  of 
phenomena:  these  pertain  to — 

1.  (a)  Moral  conceptions  and  the  thinkings  of  men. 

(6)  The  animus  of  the  soul  in  seeking  the  right  and  doing^ 
it,  and~a voiding  the  wrong.  ^  The  animus,  the  desires  of  the 
soul  in  aiming  at  moral  ends,  must  be  included  in  this 
science. 

(c)  The  moral  actions  which  the  soul  performs  and  the 
moral  ends  \^  hich  it  seeks  and  accomplishes. 

{d)  Man's  feelings,  in  view  of  the  moral  conduct  of  him- 
self and  others'7^  feelings  oj  apm-obation  and  disa^orob^jon 
towards  ourselves  and  others. 

2.  Moral  conceptions  to  be  studied  first  and  most : 

(a)  The  animus  is  practically  first.  Herein  lies  virtue  and 
vice.     But  conceptions  are  philosophically  first. 

(6)  They  explain  the  rest.  The  other  parts  thus  become 
plain  and  easy.     The  animus  will  always  be  explained  by 


the  aim.  The  actions  of  moral  life  are  those  with  which  the 
intellect  of  man  is  most  constantly  concerned. 

(c)  The  ])rincipal  controversies  concern  the  nature  of  the 
moral  law.  This  is  not  the  divine  law,  but  the  law  written 
on  the  heart  of  man. 

{d)  Tivo  fundamental  questions : 

(a)  What  is  the  essential  matter  of  the  law?  Of  what 
substance  can  moral  Tightness  be  predicated  ? 

(i3)  What  is  that  moral  rightness,  and  what  makes  it  obliga- 
tory upon  moral  beings  ?  What  are  the  peculiar  character- 
istics of  this  Tightness  and  "  obligatoriness  "  ? 

II.  METHOD   NECESSARY. 

1.  {a)  Even  in  the  simplest  undertaking  in  life. 

(b)  This  is  especially  true  when  one  part  of  the  work  con- 
ditions those  which  follow,  when  the  work  is  progressive. 

(c)  Most  of  all,  in  delicate  investigations  of  philosophy. 
We  want  to  find  the  right  method,  then  we  shall  have  a  clue. 

2.  Two  methods  in  philosophy — analytic  and  synthetic. 

(a)  Only  prominent  parts  of  philosophical  method  in 
general  are  indicated  by  these  terms. 

(b)  Not  to  be  confounded  with  analysis  and  synthesis. 
These  two  are  absolutely  inseparable  in  all  philosophical  pro- 
gress. 

(c)  Analytic  method  starts  with  analysis  and  not  synthesis. 
It  begins  witli  individual  facts  and.  ascends  to  specific,  gen- 
eric and  snprcinam  genus  when  possible. 

Synthetic  takes  ready-made  principles  and  deduces  im- 
portant truths. 

"^■((7)  Only  those  sciences  admit  of  the  Synthetic  method 
whose  principles  have  been  fully  and  clearly  ascertained — 
such  as  mathematics.  Those  sciences  embraced  under  law 
may  be  synthetic  also. 

3.  Which  method  in  Ethics  ? 
Two  departments  here: 


8 

(a)  Practical ;  here  we  may  use  the  syntheticjosiQi\io^.  We 
may  assume  some  things  which  Common  Sense  approves. 
Hence  synthesis  may  he  used  in  practical  ethics.  We  can- 
not theoretically  construct  a  whole  system  of  ethics,  we  must 
consult  human  needs,  natures,  and  experience. 

(h)  Theoretical ;  here  we  must  adhere  rigidily  to  the  analytic 
method  or  bring  confusion  into  our  system. 

III.  THREE  GENERAL  THEORIES. 

1.  Egoism  or  Selfism. 

Hef*5'TtI^moral  life  arises  from  the  pursuit  of  one's  own 
happiness,  and  we  use  the  term  Hedonists,  although  this  may 
contain  a  slander. 

(a)  Epicurus  did  not  make  pleasure  the  supreme  end  of 
life ;  he  had  a  higher  end,  viz,,  happiness. 

(6)  Paley.  Do  good  to  men.  Deny  present  gratification 
for  our  future  and  everlasting  happiness. 

2.  Utilitarianism. 

{a)  Spencer  contrasts  Egoism  and  Altruism.  There  is 
or  might  be  a  reason  according  to  which  it  may  be  our  duty 
to  devote  ourselves  wholly  to  the  good  and  happiness  of 
others.     This  doctrine  never  existed  except  in  his  philosophy. 

(6)  Aristotle  makes  the  chief  good  happiness,  and  we  obtain 
this  by  choosing  a  "golden  mean"  in  all  things. 

(c)  Bentham.     Greatest  happiness  of  the  greatest  number. 

(d)  Jonathan  Edwards.  The  great,  the  universal  duty — 
Love  of  Being  as  such,  greatest  love  to  God  as  greatest 
being,  and  special  love  to  virtuous  beings. 

(e)  These  systems  are  unsatisfactory.  We  cannot  identify 
the  right  with  what  is  useful. 

3.  Intuitionism. — No  conscious  process  in  the  perception 
of  moi^arTfutb. 

(a)  A-priori^,  truths  are  eternal  and  immediately  perceived 
by  the  mind. 

(6)  Empirical — so  called  because  it  does  not  attempt  to 
analyze  the  well-known  specifi.c  laws  of  morality.     iLappeala 


imraediately  to  man's  experience  and  ^practical  judgment. 
The  Older  Scotch  School. 

(c)  Anal.yticah  This  accepts  the  teachings  of  practical 
reason  and  seeks  Jo  draw  from  them  a  deep  and  broad  phil- 
osophy which  may  comprehend  and  explain  them  all. 

Dr.  McCosh  invites  us  to  this  last  method,  for  he  teaches 
that  "  the  intuitions  of  the  mind  "  should  be  inductively 
examined. 


LECTURE  III. 

Man's  Motive  Constitution. 


First — Man's  Natural  Constitution. 
Second — Man's  Moral  Faculty. 

I.  Man's  natural  constitution  apart  from  morality. 

{1)  Man  seeks  many  ends,  not  one  end  under  many  forms. 
Butler  says  selfishness  is  the  suicide  of  self-love.  Self-love 
seeks  happiness  of  man,  but  selfishness  defeats  its  own  ends. 

[2)  We  naturally  and  directly  seek  gratification  for  others  as 
well  as  for  ourselves — even  though  great  selfishness  exists  in 
the  world.  Man  is  not  wholly  a  selfish  being.  Sympathy 
is  a  natural  result.  Illustration :  Story  of  Robert  and 
Maggie. 

(3)  The  ends  of  desire  or  motivity  always  include  the  realization 
of  some  psychical  result.  Every  human  desire  aims  at  some 
psychical  result,  some  kind  of  spiritual  gratification.  Even 
Instinct  seeks  such  ends.  The  instinct  of  an  animal  desires 
some  useful  result  without  the  knowledge  of  the  animal. 
Bees  build  hexagonal  cells  because  of  some  pleasure  in  doing 
so.  A  hen  on  eggs  has  a  natural  gratification  but  no  brood 
of  chickens,  before  her  mind.  When  we  rise  from  instincts 
to  appetites  we  seek  some  psychical  result,  e.  y.,  removal  of 
hunger.    When  we  rise  from  appetites  to  propensities  we 


10 

must  always  have  a  personal  experience  in  view.  He  who 
seeks  for  power  would  hold  the  reins. 

{4)  Reason  constructs  ends  on  the  basis  of  other  ends  which 
present  themselves  without  rational  thought. 

What  Butler  says  of  self-interest  is  true  of  all  the  rational 
motivities  of  man.  Man  is  capable  of  many  kinds  of  grati- 
fication. The  benevolent  man  seeks  to  relieve  suffering  and 
advance  the  best  interests  of  the  human  race.  The  structure 
of  man's  nature  is  like  the  classes  in  society,  the  upper  rest 
upon  the  lower. 

[5)  Reason  modifies  the  other  motivities  of  man  by  conforming 
them  to  her  own  ends,  and  assigns  them  grades  among  each  other. 
Reason  without  giving  morality  to  ends  may  rationalize  them, 
and  this  is  the  great  difference  between  brute  and  human 
affections. 

Reason  has  ends  of  her  own,  takes  the  lead,  and  assigns  to 
all  other  motivities  their  proper  places. 

II.  ANALOGICAL  CONJECTURES. 

The  Moral  faculty. 

(-?)  This  may  have  peculiar  ends  of  its  own,  differing  from 
all  others.  If  self-love  and  benevolence  each  has  its  own 
end,  the  moral  faculty  may  have  its  own  end  also. 

[S)  It  may  construct  these  after  and  upon  other  ends — other 
and  lower  ends.  This  would  make  the  moral  faculty  analo- 
gous to  common  reason. 

(3)  It  may  have  psychical  results  as  essential  parts  of  its 
ends. 

(4)  It  may  regulate  life  by  requiring  conformity  and  sub- 
ordination to  itself  in  seeking  its  own  ends.  In  som  i  systems 
the  conscience  is  wholly  regulative.  But  it  has  ends  of  its 
own,  and  also  regulates. 

(5)  It  may,  intellectually  speaking,  be  a  very  high  faculty, 
and  that  showing  the  greatest  practical  wisdom.  Natural 
reason  is  comprehensive,  looking  into  the  future  and  organ- 
izing the  ends  ot  man.  So  moral  reason  may=wisdom,  the 
highest  form  of  which  is  found  in  God  alone. 


11 
LECTURE  IV. 

Ends  or  Final  Cause. 

How  is  an  end  a  cauge  ? 

Only  as  the  conception  of  the  end  may  bej^n.nRRt.ivp..  An 
end,  the  last  of  a  thing;  but  here  we  speak  of  that  which 
exists  at  or  before  the  very  beginning  of  a  work  and  con- 
tinues throughout  the  whole  course.  There  may  be  a  final 
cause,  as  in  the  case  of  ten  billiard  balls  lying  in  contact — 
number  nine  gives  final  cause  of  motion  to  ball  number  ten. 
But  we  do  not  mean  this. 

We  speak  of  a  cause,  which  is  a  result  and  of  a  consum- 
mation which  is  a  cause.  One  of  these  must  be  figurative, 
and  since  the  cause  cannot  be,  the  end  must.  The  same  thing 
is  set  forth  in  these  terms  in  two  lights.  We  shall  consider 
it  in  each  light : 

I.  ^nal  cause  is  the  more  literal  expression. 

[1)  These  causes  may  literally  exist,  and  are  then  the  motive 
conceptions  of  the  mind — those  which  lead  us  to  ifntifiF  "P"" 
anyplan  of  work  or^joceclure.  A  "  final  cause  entered 
the  heart  of  Columbus  and  carried  him  to  the  end  of  his 
work. 

{2)  They  do  not  in  themselves  have  any  efficiency,  and  are 
to  be  distinguished  from  efficient  causes.  This  distinction 
is  made  and  unmade  by  Aristotle.  He  illustrated  his  four 
causes  by  a  statue  :  Material,  the  marble;  formal,  the  beau- 
tiful form;  efficient,  mental  skill  and  muscular  aptness  of  the 
sculptor;  fiiml,  desire  of  fame  and  production  of  an  object  of 
beauty.  This  beginning  must  be  approved,  but  when 
Aristotle  goes  on  to  apply  his  doctrine  of  causes,  he  becomes 
confused,  and  instead  of  four  different  causes  he  gives  us 
four  which  all  partake  more  or  less  of  the  "  efficient  cause." 
The  material  and  formal  have  a  tendency,  naturally,  to  unite; 
back  of  these  is  the  efficient,  which  keeps  these  moving. 
Final  cause  is  back  of  all  these,  and  gives  useful  ends  to  all 
the  dilferent  operations  of  the  universe. 


12 

(3)  In  what  sense  may  we  speak  of  final  causes  and  their 
causality  ?  The  modern  doctrine  of  cause  is  not  simply  that 
of  an  efficient  agency,  but  of  that  agent  considered  as  com- 
bined and  united  with  all  the  diff'erejb  conditions  which  are 
necessary  to  the  actual  production  of  the  phenomenon. 
Illustration:  Cannon  discharging  solid  shot.  We  may  say 
that  the  motion  of  the  ball  lay  in  the  explosive  nature  of  the 
powder,  but  we  would  have  to  take  in  also  the  structure  of 
the  gun,  position  of  ball,  powder  to  be  ignited,  etc.  We 
often  speak  of  many  things  as  causes,  besides  that  thing  in 
which  the  efficiency  resides. 

Then  a  condition  may  be  spoken  of  as  a  cause,  because 
necessary  to  the  final  result :  e.  g.,  a  boiler  explodes  because 
there  is  a  lack  of  water  in  it;  here  the  want  of  water  is  only 
the  condition  necessary  to  the  overheating  of  the  boiler;  and 
in  this  way  we  speak  of  Final  causes. 

II.  We  often  speak  of  an  object  as  an  end,  and  not  of  the  con- 
ception of  the  object  as  a  final  cause.  We  speak  of  cause  as 
of  something  in  the  mind,  but  of  end  as  of  something  which 
attracts  mind  to  it. 

{!)  An  end  does  not  literally  exist.  It  is  an  ideal  object, 
not  real,  but  to  be  realized.  Illustration:  Napoleon's  object 
was  to  be  Emperor  of  France  and  Dictator  of  Europe.  But 
after  he  became  Emperor  this  was  an  end  no  longer. 

Moral  law=a  collection  of  practical  ideas  which  the  human 
mind  employs  and  uses  for  its  own  end;*. 

All  these  ideas  of  imagination  are  constructed  by  the 
mind  from  elements  obtained  from  the  cognition  of  things 
in  the  actual  world,  and  they  look  to  a  consummation  in 
man's  present  or  future  life. 

{2)  Ends  are  objects  characterized  ab  extra,  yet  each  also 
as  having  a  nature  of  its  own.  When  one  thing  corres- 
ponds to  another  that  thing  must  correspond  to  the  first. 

Story — Sorely  smitten,  soft  young  man  in  Hanover  College. 

[3)  Strictly,  every  end  is  an  ultimate  object  of  pursuit.  The 
very  definition   involves   this.     Some   distinguish  between 


13 

ultimate  and  proximate  ends,  but  tliis  is  of  no  radical  im- 
portance. Ethics  mentions  proximate  or  mediate  ends  only 
to  say  they  are  not  the  objects  of  its  discussions,  save  as  con- 
nected with  true  or  ultimate  ends. 


LECTURE  V. 

Moral  Actions. 


Actions  constitute  an  important  part  of  moral  life.  The 
moral  law  is  a  collection  of  practical  conceptions  which  man 
is  bound  to  realize  in  action. 

I.  Actions  in  general  are  of  the  following  varieties :  For 
the  human  mind  has  power  to  expand  the  conceptions  em- 
bodied in  words.  "  Man  is  mortal,"  includes  not  only  man, 
but  every  woman,  child,  etc.  Human  language  tends 
towards  the  expansion  or  contraction  of  our  ideas.  -,  '-y 

(1)  A  mere  e.rcrcisc  of  power.    This  is  the  simplest  and  most    ^^'"'  ^^    ''•'^ 
radical  idea — e.  g.,  the  boy  runs,  wind  blows.     But  there  is 
no  action  which  does  not  produce  some  result,  otherwise  we 
would    contradict    the    doctrine    of    the    "  conservation    of 
energy."     We  may  call  these  actions  intransitive.  , 

{S)  An  exercise  of  power  so  as  to  2)roduce_a,result—e.  g.,  fire    /'^Tt-i.i-it'^^ 
hardens  clay.     This  has  in  it,  as  an  essential  part,  the  eftect- 
uation  6f~a.  result.     These  we  may  call  transitive — passing  of 
a  power  from  the  agent  to  the  thing  acted  upon.  '  , 

{3)  An  intentional^  exercise  of  power  so   as   to   produce   a  f-ittlivtiM^  /t 
result.     We   say  the  orator  addressed   the   people.     Here 
there  is  an  enlargement  of  our  conception,  and  we  take  into 
consideration  the  intention  had  in  view  in  the  effectuation  of  a 
result. 

Here  we  may  also  class  all  those  actions  where  a  person 
endeavors  to  effect  an  end  and  fails  or  misses  his  aim. 
Hence  we  say  there  is  an  attemptive  as  well  as  an  effective 
action — e.  g.^  hunter  wounding  bird.     Such   actions  fully 


14 

agree  and  coincide  with  intentional  actions  as  far  as  the  in- 
tentions and  resolutions  of  man  to  perform  go.  Hence 
these  occupy  an  important  place  in  human  and  divine  law. 
A  man  endeavoring  to  do  his  duty  is  reckoned  guiltless 
though  he  fail,  as  a  pilot  or  engineer. 
,    •  »  ___j_j         (^)  An  intentional  doing  of  something  from,  a  given  animus  or 

fi^-^-'H^Cfi-/^^^-^ YRotivity.  We  think  of  the  life  of  some  conquerors,  and  say 
it  was  full  of  ambitious  actions,  or  that  of  a  philanthropist 
full  of  benevolent  actions.  Hence,  from  the  spirit,  we  class 
actions  as  "  base,"  "  honorable,"  "  ignoble,"  and  "  interested  " 
actions. 

Actions,  therefore,  are  intransitive,  transitive,  intentional, 
desideraiive.  These  difi'erent  classes  are  not  so  distinguished 
as  that  the  same  radical  activity  can  not  belong  to  two,  or 
even  all  four,  at  once. 

An  intransitive  action  is  so  called  because  of  that  particu- 
lar view  and  conception  which  the  mind  takes  of  it,  and  not 
of  its  own  intrinsic  nature. 

The  same  is  true  of  transitive  actions.  Hence  a  transi- 
tive action  is  often  founded  upon  and  has  an  intransitive 
aspect.  Sometimes  transitive  actions  may  be  conceived  of 
as  intransitive.  But  we  can  not  make  an  intransitive  action 
the  object  of  an  intentional  doing. 

The  intentional  embraces  less  than  the  desiderative. 

The  desiderative  is  founded  upon  the  intentional.  The 
intentional  is  the  desiderative  viewed  in  a  more  limited 
light.  We  are  not  acquainted  with  a  man's  motives,  and 
hence  we  may  consider  an  action  merely  intentional.  The 
desiderative  is  related  to  the  intentional  as  the  transitive  is 
to  the  intransitive. 

II.  MORAL  ACTIONS. 

(_?)  No  action  ?>  moral  simplg  as  an  exercise  of  power,  or  even 
as  effectuating  a  result — c.  g.,  the  wind  blows.  In  order  to  have 
a  moral  character  they  must  have  so^^elation  to  aj'ational_ 
being.     Story — Johnnie  Schoonmaker. 


15 

(2)  Every  moral  action^  fully,  considered,  is  both  the  infentional 
and  the' desiderative  effectuation  of  n  result,  or  at  least  an  in- 
tentional  and  desiderative  attempt.  Moral  action  is  not 
always  the  actual  effectuation  of  a  result.  An  attempted 
assassination  would  make  the  man  an  assassin,  even  though 
he  failed.  The  moral  action  includes  the  intention  and 
peculiar  animus. 

(3)  Actions  as  morally  right  and  wrong  are  merely  inteyitional, 
but  as  virtuous  and  vicious  they  are  desiderative  also.     An  ac- 

"no^naybe  righf  wliifeyet  it  is  not  virtuous,  A  man  who 
is  honest  because  honesty  is  the  best  policy  does  right,  but 
he  is  only  a  politic  and  selfish  man.  A  wrong  action  can 
not  be  done  without  a  vicious  animus,  though  a  right  action 
may  be  done  without  a  virtuous  animus.  Any  wrong  action 
is  the  intentional  effectuation  of  what  is  bad — the  words  used 
to  denote  wrong  acts  carry  with  them  an  idea  of  viciousness. 

(4)  The  word  "intentional"  here  signifies  either  inten- 
tionable  or  intended  at  least,  or  they  could  have  no  place  or 
care  in  a  moral  law.  Irish  policeman  threatens  one  for 
breaking  an  unknown  law. 

No  action  can  have  a  moral  nature  which  is  not  actually 
or  possibly  related  to  the  understanding  of  a  moral  being. 

{5)  We  should  distinguish  between  what  is  absolutely  and 
divinely  right  and  what  is  humanly  or  relatively  so.  This 
will  clear  up  difficulties  and  perplexities.  Men  sometimes 
looked  upon  slavery  as  divine.  So,  in  consequence  of  hu- 
man infirmity,  what  is  absolutely  wrong  may  be  relatively 
right,  and  vice  versa. 


1} 

LECTURE  VI.      ^  V 

Moral  Reason  or  Conscience. 

To  understand  moral  laws  and  actions  we  should  under- 
stand the  nature  of  the  Moral  Faculty,  and  this,  in  itself,  is 
worthy  of  study.  "We  shall  consider  Jirst — the  nature  of  its 
operations,  and  second — its  principal  products. 

The  faculty  may  be  viewed  under  three  lights  and  under 
three  names.  !No  study  throws  more  light  on  our  ideas  than 
the  careful  study  of  synonyms.  It  is  very  seldom,  indeed, 
that  two  words  or  names  are  completely  synonymous. 

(1)  Conscience — conscientia — (ToveiSrjcn^.  If  we  viewed  only 
its  etymological  meaning  we  would  jB.nd  it=consciousness^ 
concomitant  knowing,  and  indeed  originally  among  the 
Scholastics  conscience  did  mean  consciousnes.  The  idea  of  a 
concomitant  knowledge  may  have  a  two-fold  meaning.  Man 
has  thoughts,  desires,  feelings,  but  he  can  also  observe  these 
as  they  flow  along.  Then  there  is  another  concomitant 
knowledge  which  follows  and  exists  together  with  other 
states — e.  ^.,  beautiful  young  maiden  pleasing  a  company  and 
conscious  of  it.  This  adds  a  new  and  different  meaning  to 
the  word.  Now  conscience  is  rather  of  the  latter  kind ; 
for,  knowing  our  lives  we  may  also  know  them  in  their  moral 
relations. 

[2)  Moral  sense — a  power  of  cognition  accompanied  by  a 
power  of  feeling,  yet  not  merely  the  result  of  feelings.  The 
Latin  word,  sentio,  indicates  that  cognition  which  takes  place 
in  connection  with  feeling. 

In  English  the  first  and  simple  meaning  of  sense  is  seen 
when  we  contrast  it  with  intellect.  Then  sense  signifies 
sense  perception.  Used  in  a  higher  meaning  it  loses  almost 
entirely  all  idea  of  feeling — e.  g.,  a  man  of  good  sense. 

The  Greek  word — alada-voimi — gives  us  the  intellectual 
character  in  stronger  form.  JEsthetics=that  exercise  and 
judgment  of  taste  by  which   we  discover  the  elements  of 


17 

beauty  and  have  a  corresponding  feeling.  The  Germans 
give  it  a  wider  significance  and  include  morals.  The  truth 
to  be  noted  is  that  it  is  the  peculiar  quality  of  moral  percep- 
tions to  rouse  within  us  feelings  which  correspond  to  the 
nature  of  the  actions  contemplated. 

{3)  Right  or  Moral  Reason — is  the  best  term  philosophically 
when  properly  restricted.  It  is  so  called  not  because  it  is 
any  more  right  than  any  other  reason.  Right  Reason  is 
directed  toward  moral  rightness. 

Limitations — [a]  Reason  has  an  intuitive  as  well  as  a  dis- 
cursive mode.  Some  men  look  upon  it  only  as  the  discur- 
sive power. 

Locke.  Reason^that  faculty  of  intelligence  whereby  man 
and  his  intellect  is  distinguished  from  the  brute  and  his  in- 
telligence. 

Hamilton.  Reason=that  comprehending  and  penetrating 
power  of  the  human  intellect  whereby  it  is  enabled  to  have 
a  complete  and  satisfactory  knowledge  of  things.  It  may 
be  exercised  synthetically  or  analytically. 

(6)  Reason  may  be  motive  as  well  as  intellectual.  Mere 
thought  has  no  motivity,  but  the  soul  has  motivity  and  it  is 
a  condition  of  the  soul's  motivity  that  it  should  have 
thought. 

If  we  allow,  then,  that  the  soul  has  moral  motivities,  we 
can  easily  enlarge  and  amplify  the  meaning  of  reason. 
Hence,  Moral  or  Right  Reason  is  the  best  term  for  our  moral 
faculty. 


LECTURE  VII. 

The  Conceptions  of  the  Moral  Reason. 

These  are  distinguished  from  those  of  the  Speculative 
Reason  in  being  Motive,  hence,  the  Moral  Reason  may  be 
considered  a  particular  development  of  the  Practical  Reason. 

I.  Moral  ends.     Some  ethical  systems  speak  of  ends  almost 

2 


18 

exclusively.  Egoism  or  Epicureanism  has  an  end  of  personal 
ease  or  pleasure.  When  we  rise  to  Utilitarianism  the  end  is 
very  proniinent,  though  here  not  a  personal  end  but  the 
welfare  of  all  who  are  affected  by  our  actions — "  greatest  good 
of  the  greatest  number." 

Other  systems  look  almost  exclusively  to  actions.  Alex- 
ander, in  his  moral  science,  gives  almost  no  reference  to 
moral  ends.  He  says  our  desires  and  motivities  have  a 
moral  character,  but  makes  no  mention  of  ends  as  having  a 
moral  character. 

Both  these  errors  are  to  be  avoided.  Moral  actions  involve 
ends — they  are  the  intentional  effectuation  of  a  result.  The 
doctrine  of  ends  is  absolutely  necessary,  but  a  system  look- 
ing to  ends  alone  is  defective.  Moral  ends  are  an  important 
class  of  conceptions  formulated  by  the  Moral  Reason. 

The  end  of  punitive  justice  is  the  rebuke  of  sin,  the  main- 
tenance of  law,  the  establishment  and  continuance  of  God's 
moral  government  over  rational  beings. 

II.  Actions,  or  doings,  as  right  and  wrong — and  hence  jpositively 
and  negatively  obligatory.  Some  actions  are  in  themselves 
true  and  ultimate  moral  ends. 

Actions  are  right  or  wrong,  per  se  or  essentiam,  and  per 
accidens  or  consequens.  Simply  stated,  some  actions  are  in- 
herently, necessarily  and  eternally  right  and  wrong,  but 
others  are  right  and  wrong  only  from  surrounding  circum- 
stances. This  divides  rigbt  and  obligatory  actions  from  one 
another,  and  does  not  divide  right  and  obligatory  from  those 
which  are  not  right  and  obligatory.  Those  actions  which  in 
their  full  development  are  essentially  wrong  may  be  con- 
tracted and  include  actions  which  are  not  wrong  per  se. 
Many  actions  are  right  ^er  se,  and  only  by  a  special  contrac- 
tion of  view  can  a  part  of  them  per  accidens  be  deemed 
right.  Ordinary  business  transactions  may  take  on  a  moral 
character. 

III.  Moral  agents  and  their  desires  and  doings  as  obligated  or 
bound.     We  now  speak   of  actions  as  due  or  obligated  in 


19 

addition  to  being  right  or  wrong.  The  agent  and  his  actions 
and  desires  cannot  be  separated  in  reality.  But  we  may 
separate  and  speak  of  them  by  abstraction. 

That  which  primarily  binds  is  the  moral  end,  that  which 
is  primarily  bound  is  the  moral  desire.  There  may  be 
cases  of  duty  where  a  man  can  do  nothing,  still  it  is  his  duty 
to  desire  to  do  that  duty. 

Actions  are  due  or  bound  as  effective  or  conducive  to  the 
moral  end.  The  same  action  in  different  relations  is  either 
right  and  obligatory,  or  obligated  and  bound.  To  speak 
of  an  action  as  right  and  obligatory  is  not  the  same  as  to 
speak  of  it  as  due  and  bound. 

As  actions  and  desires  are  simply  abstract  ways  of  con- 
sidering persons  as  acting  and  desiring,  the  ultimate  truth 
may  be  expressed  by  saying  that  the  person  is  bound  to  do 
or  to  desire.  \ 

IV.  We  conceive  of  human  character^  life  and  conduct  as  virtu- 
ous or  as  vicious.  The  conceptions  already  discussed  pertain 
directly  to  the  moral  law.  Ends,  right  actions,  duty,  are 
conceptions  of  the  moral  law ;  virtue  and  vice  set  forth  the 
realized  effect  of  the  law  as  obeyed  or  broken.  The  concep- 
tion of  conduct  as  virtuous,  or  as  vicious,  is  more  compre- 
hensive than  any  of  the  other  conceptions  considered. 


LECTURE  VIII. 
The  Moral  Law. 


In  Ethics  we  deal  with  two  fundamental  questions :  First^ 
_the  body;  of  ,_the_aiomLIaw  :  what  is  that  essential  nature  of 
that  of  which  moral  rightness  and  obligatoriness  may  be 
predicated?  and,  second,  whatisthe  nature  of  this  obliga- 
toriness ? 

I.  Bi/  the  Moral  Law  we  do  not  mean  the  law  as  published  by 
divine  authority,  but  the  law  as  natwdly  known  to  mankind.     The 


20 

divine  law  is,  without  question,  the  most  perfect  expression  of 
it  for  all  moral  creatures.  We  look  at  the  law  of  God,  as 
understood  without  revelation,  as  written  on  the  heart  of  man. 
"We  find  that  it  consists  of  certain  general  conceptions  which 
men  naturally  form,  fixing  their  ends  of  pursuit  and  modes 
of  activity.  To  be  honest,  truthful,  obedient  to  parents, 
concerned  for  the  public  good  and  peace — these  are  the 
spontaneous  dictates  of  man's  nature. 

II.  This  law  cannot  be  accounted  for  by  materialistic  philoso- 
phers. This  is  scarcely  worthy  of  consideration.  Matter 
cannot  act  upon  matter  to  produce  a  conscience  or  a  moral 
rule. 

Two  theories  have  divided  men  : 

(i)  There  is  an  ultimate  and  universal  nature  in  which 
these  moral  ideas  reside.  These  ideas  being  "  everywhere, 
and  every  when"  they  become  specially  present  in  the  mind 
of  God  and  in  the  minds  of  his  rational  creatures. 

(^)  This  law  is_not  an  immediate  per.ceptiou  of  the  "  Ulti- 
mate Reason."  Moral  rules  are  formed  by  the  mind  in  the 
same  way  as  other  rules,  i.  e.,  by  generalization  from  indi- 
vidual cases  of  duty.  None  of  these  rules  are  the  original  pos- 
sessions of  the  mind.  All  our  earliest  ideas  are  specific  and 
individual^  and  from  these  we  rise  to  general  ideas.  We  do 
get  some  things  from  parents  and  older  people,  but  these 
rules  came  originally  by  generalization.  Every  man  has 
power  to  judge  of  the  morality  of  these  rules. 

III.  This  laiojias  an  inhexerit  sujprerae  authority.  Sometimes 
we  say  that  conscience  is  supreme ;  sometimes  that  duty  is 
obligatory.  Conscience  is  a  faculty  which  claims  to  regu- 
late all  things  for  us.  This  is  true,  but  conscience  is  only  an 
interpreter  of  the  law,  e.  g.^  Supreme  judges  of  U.  S.  Court. 
When  we  say  that  "duty  is  obligatory,"  we  recognize  a  su- 
perlative obligation,  from  which  we  cannot  escape.  This  is 
true,  but  what  are  these  duties  which  draw  and  bind  us  ? 
They  do  not  as  yet  exist;  they  are  ideal  and  not  real  things, 


21 

to  be  realized  in  our  future  conduct.  It  is  best  to  say, 
"  Law  is  supreme."  Law^a  collection  and  simplification 
of  all  those  dutiful  ideals  which  are  binding  upon  the 
soul.  There  is  no  place  where  we  can  be  free  from  the  re- 
quirements of  duty,  no  time  in  life  when  we  are  free  from 
moral  law. 

IV.  TJic  Idir  cn))si.'^fs  of  commandments  and  prohibitions,  i.  e., 
of  things  right,  good  and  obligatory  to  do  or  seek,  and  of 
things  wrong,  .eyil,  ^^)^^  obligatory  not  to  do  or  seek.  It  has 
thus  a  positive  and  a  negative  character.  In  Christian  duty 
we  have  commandments  and  prohibitions.  Actions  as  right 
and  wrong  are  not  related  to  each  other  as  merely  privative. 
There  are  actions  which  are  indifiterent.  Wrong  is  not 
simply  opposition  to  right;  it  has  in  it  something  inherently 
and  p)ositiveiy  wrong.  We  should  study  the  right  before  the 
wrong,  because  all  rational  beings  are  and  must  be  striving 
toward  right  as  their  goal. 

V.  Certain  senses  of  the  adjective  ^^ right"  and  the  noun 
*^ right"  are  to  be  distinguished  from  that  moral  Rightness 
which  is  the  basis  of  obligations,  and  which  is  the  distin- 
guishing characteristic  of  the  moral  law.  By  "  right " 
things  we  mean  what  the  law  sets  forth  as  good  and  obliga- 
tory upon  moral  beings,  and  not  either  "rights,"  or  "things 
not  wrong." 


LECTURE  IX. 

Primary  Generalization. 

In  Ethics  we  deal  with  two  fundamental  questions : 
First,  The  body  of  the  moral  law ;  what  is  the  nature  ot 
that  of  which  moral  rightness  and  obligatoriness  may  be 
predicated  ?  Secoiid,  What  is  the  nature  of  that  obligatori- 
ness ?  Now,  which  of  these  two  shall  we  understand  first  ? 
Many  have  considered  the  question  of  moral  rightness  as 


22 

something  immediately  known  by  intuitive  or  practical 
reason. 

The  matter  of  the  law  should  he  studied  in  order  to  an 
understanding  of  its  own  nature  and  its  rightness.  In  phys- 
ical science,  to  determine  the  nature  of  the  directive  ten- 
dency of  loadstone  we  accumulate  a  mass  of  facts — needles, 
magnets,  electric  currents,  currents  over  the -earth — in  all 
these  we  seek  the  cause  of  this  directive  tendency.  Thus 
an  ascending  generalization  results. 

So  we  direct  our  attention  to  the  matter  of  the  moral  law, 
seeking  the  common  nature  which  belongs  to  all  right  actions 
and  ends. 

It  will  be  an  ascending  generalization  by  elimination. 
The  great  claims  of  actions  are  right  and  obligatory  apart 
from  their  'peculiarities;  there  must  be  some  feature  which 
renders  them  all  right  and  obligatory. 

Our  generalizations  need  not  begin  absolutely  with  in- 
dividual instances.  Men  have  fashioned  many  general  con- 
ceptions of  right  and  wrong,  and  these  are  practically  all  we 
need.  Philosophically,  they  may  not  be  correct  or  ultimate 
or  exclusive.  Their  object  is  ^^radi'ra/,  not  speculative.  All 
scientists  use  more  or  less  ordinary  classifications.  So  we 
would  begin  with  conceptions  of  duty  found  in  the  ordinary 
mind  and  language  of  mankind.  Here  we  must  explain 
terms.  In  English  we  are  necessitated  to  use  terms  which 
refer  rather  to  the  virtues  than  to  the  duties  themselves. 
Still  we  can  indicate  duties  by  terms  expressive  of  the  cor- 
responding virtues. 

Four  great. classes  of  Virtues  and  Duty  : 

1.  Moral  Goodness. 

2.  Moral  Esteem. 

3.  Regulative  Righteousness. 

4.  Causative  Righteousness. 

We  neglect  the  prohibitions  of  the  law,  presenting  only 
the  positive  side,  since  an  understanding  of  the  positive 
side  will  lead  to  an  understanding  of  the  negative  side. 


23 

I.     MORAL  GOODNESS. 

We  can  use  the  term  Moral  Goodness  in  a.,Y,Qr,y  '!^i^^- 
sense,  including  every  form  of  beneficence  and  benevolence, 
anything  that  aims  at  the  happiness  and  welfare  of  human 
beings.  This  virtue  manifests  itself  in  two  ways :  (1)  the 
relief  of  wretchedness  and  sorrow,  and  (2)  the  production  of 
happiness  and  gladness.  It  not  only  does  good,  but  also 
cEerishes  the  spirit  of  love  in  our  hearts  for  all  beings. 
Love  for  God  and  for  man  is  the  "  fulfilling  "  of  the  law. 

TI.     MOEAL  ESTEEM. 

Moral  Esteem  gives  special  regard  and  treatment  to  rational 
beings  according  to  their  moral  characte;".  It  says  practi- 
cally: Do  good  to  all  men,  but  especially  to  those  who  are 
upright  and  virtuous.  There  are  two  ways  of  exercising 
this  :  We  must  shew  a  special  practical  favor  to  good  men, 
to  those  who  are  of  the  "  household  of  faith."  This  does 
not  require  evil  of  us,  though  under  certain  circumstan- 
ces w^e  must  withdraw  our  practical  kindness  and  regard 
from  those  who  are  unworthy  of  it.  The  second  manifesta- 
tion is  exhibited  in  special  love  to  the  virtuous— spiritual 
brotherhood,  God  for  our  father  and  Christ  for  our  elder 
brother. 

Moral  beings  may  sink  to  such  a  state  as  to  be  no  longer 
the  proper  object  of  the  love  of  rational  beings.  This  law 
does  not  conflict  with  Moral  Goodness.  It  operates  more 
fully  in  affections  than  in  actions. 

III.     REGULATIVE  RIGHTEOUSNESS. 

Regulative  Righteousness,  or  Righteousness,  simply  urges 
all  the  ordinary  rules  of  right  conduct,  Justitia  generalise  or 
general  justice.  We  saj'  Regulative  Righteousness  because 
the  aim  is  not  positive,  and  is  not  to  advance  the  general 
welfare  of  mankind,  but  to  keep  men  from  seeking  ends 
conflicting  with  the  requirements  of  duty.  It  includes  all 
the  morality  that  is  enforced  in  human  courts,  and  all  rules 


24 

of  right  and  honorable  dealing.  There  are  many  things 
which  we  do — pay  debts,  abstain  from  wrong  language — 
that  are  manifestations  of  Righteousness,  but  not  of  Moral 
Goodness.  The  legislation  of  courts  and  civil  law  fall 
under  this  form.  It  has  its  affectional  as  well  as  its  practi- 
cal development.  There  are  natural  affections  and  disposi- 
tions which  we  must  exercise — modesty,  humility,  liberality, 
and  chastity.  These  natural  dispositions  of  themselves 
have  no  moral  character,  if  not  rightly  regulated  they  may 
degenerate  into  feelings  that  are  wrong — modesty  may  be- 
come awkward  bashfulness.  They  are  virtuous  when  regu- 
lated. 

IV.     CAUSATIVE  RIGHTEOUSNESS. 

Causative  Righteousness  is  that  which  aims  to  cause 
righteousness  and  moral  excellence  of  every  kind.  It  is  a 
duty  in  which  virtue  is  causative  of  itself.  It  may  be  in- 
formal or  formal.  Its  ground  is  two-fold — we  may  simply 
desire  honest  things  to  be  done  for  their  own  inherent 
Tightness;  or  we  may  promote  virtue  as  moral  good. 

Its  prominent  development  is  JRectoral  Righteousness,  and 
of  this  the  most  important  development  is  Punitive  Righteous- 
ness=Ju8tice.  This  occupies  a  large  place  both  in  human 
and  divine  government. 


LECTURE  X. 
Moral  Grocdness. 


Moral  goodness  should  come  first  because  of  its  very  sim- 
plicity, having  one  great  aim,  and  that  positive.  Regulative 
Righteousness  has  a  preventive  application,  but  Moral  Good- 
ness gives  us  only  a  progressive  aim.  We  introduce  two  new 
terms,  Practive  and  Commotive. 

We  have  already  distinguished  between  the  duty  of  benefi- 
cence and  benevolence,  also  practical  and  affectional  duties 


25 

of  Regulative  Righteousness  ;  one  consists  of  doing  rightly, 
the  other  consists  of  cherishing  right  feelings  within  our 
hearts.  We  have  as  yet  no  word  for  those  moral  motivities 
which  aim  at  those  duties,  hence  we  propose  Practive  and 
Commotive.  Practive  aims  at_  practical__activity  and  Com- 
motive  aims  at  cherishing  internal  moti_ves.  There  is  a  dif- 
ference between  the  affection  and  the  moral  motivity  which 
aims  at  that  affection ;  the  motivity  mingles  with  the  affection 
which  it  aims  to  cherish  and  regulate.  We  need  so  to  dis- 
tinguish because  the  affection  may  be  in  some  cases  right 
and  in  others  wrong. 

L  The  law  of  Practive  Goodness  is  "  Do  Good."  Good 
is  happiness  or  whatever  contributes  to^bappiness — what- 
ever banishes  pain  or  diminishes  the  amount  of  misery  in 
the  world.  The  loss  of  good  or  actual  causation  of  misery 
are  both  alike  bad.  A  drunkard  finds  enjoyment  and  not 
happiness,  for  the  wretchedness  and  misery  far  exceeds  the 
enjoyment. 

Happiness  is  the  ultimate  end  sought  by  Moral  Goodness 
or  beneficence,  and  as  secondary  whatsoever  serves  or  pro- 
motes happiness.  Merchants  call  their  articles  "  goods," 
health,  strength  are  good;  from  these  we  rise  in  the  scale 
until  we  enter  into  the  moral  sphere  and  find  the  virtues  of 
the  human  soul  the  highest  good.  Dr.  Hopkins.  The  second- 
ary forms  are  good  for  something,  but  happiness  as  the  ulti- 
mate good  is  "  good  for  nothing,"  Happiness  is  not  good  for 
anything  bej^ond  itself. 

II.  Thoconception  good  is  most  fiexible  and  applies  to  a  great 
variety  of  things.  "Pain  is  not  an  evil  to  a  wise  man" — 
it  conies  for  our  discipline  and  development  in  manhood. 
The  term  is  applied  to  the  transitory  amusements  and  pleas- 
ures of  the  present  hour — again  to  the  blessedness  of  the 
saints  throughout  all  eternity. 

Hence  Practive  Moral  Goodness  is  most  comprehensive 
in  its  scope;  we  must  seek  and  promote  every  form  of  good. 
The  lowest  form  of  good  is  comfort  and  gratification.     Story 


26 

— Irish  peasant  woman  :     "  I've  had  haith  a  warmin'  and 
afillin'."     James  2:  16. 

This  duty  becomes  very  excellent  when  it  assumes  a  per- 
manent form. 

III.  The  good  at  which  Moral  Goodness  aims  is  sought 
under  a  ynost  absolute  and  unrestricted  view  of  man's  practical 
relations.  It  is  all  the  good  of  wTiich  the  case  admits,  or  a  part 
of  that  total  considered  as  part  of  it.  We  may  take  limited 
views  of  good.  We  may  pursue  only  one  kind  of  good ;  or 
the  good  of  only  one  individual,  or  of  only  one  class  of  indi- 
viduals, excluding  others.  We  should  contribute  to  every 
form  of  good  to  which  our  actions  can  lend  an  aid.  We 
should  seek  good  purely  and  simply  and  all  the  good  attain- 
able in  the  case. 

IV.  It  is  not  easy  to  find  a  name  for  so  comprehensive  a 
conception.  The  term  "  good  "  is  but  a  feeble  expression 
when  called  to  take  in  both  earthly  things  and  the  blessedness 
of  the  saints  in  heaven.  It  is  generally  bound  to  some  limited 
object  and  aim;  but  no  phrase  is  better  than  "  Absolute  Good." 
This  law  of  moral  good  is  not  Utilitarian,  because  (a)  it  is  not 
confined  to  any  low  view  of  good,  and  (6)  it  concerns  only 
one  department  of  duty  and  not  the  whole  law.  Absolute 
Good  and  the  Summum  Bonum  are  not  identical. 

We  must  seek  whatever  is  right  and  good  for  its  own 
sake,  and  virtue  is  the  highest  and  purest  good.  This  illus- 
trates the  exceedingly  rational  character  of  the  Moral 
Faculty  and  what  we  mean  by  Rational  Intuitionism. 


LECTURE  XI. 

Commotive  Goodness. 

These  distinctions  of  Tractive  and  Commotive  Goodness 
somewhat  run  counter  to  common  thought  and  language. 
We  commonly  distinguish  aflfections  and  desires,  not  as 
actions,  as  the  springs  and  causes  of  actions. 


27 
I.   Commoiive  Virtue  in  general  is  conditioned 


[T)  On  the  existence  of  desires  ;)nd  affections. 
,  [2)  On  a  self-regard  or  intelligent  consciousness. 
{3)  A  power  of  guiding  the  attention  to  objects  of  desire. 

All  motivities  whatever  spring  from  the  consideration  of 
such  objects.  This  power  resembles  the  helm  of  a  great 
ship — the  ship  cannot  escape  winds  and  waves,  but  it  can  use 
both  to  drive  it  to  its  destination.  We  cannot  stifle  desires 
but  we  have  power  to  control  them. 

(^)  A  rationalit£,^hich  may  use  this  power  for  one's  self- 
control  and  guidance.  Brutes  have  no  attentive  conscious- 
ness  r  T^Hey  cannot  control  their  lives  as  the  human  spirit. 
Man  has  a  rational  power  which  devises  ends,  compares  ends 
and  seeks  some  of  them.  Reason  claims  a  superiority,  to 
be  a  ruler,  a  judge  of  the  other  motivities  of  the  human  soul. 

II.  Commoiive  Goodness— -xiQgaXvfQXj. 

(i)  Benevolence  is  not  all  virtue  or  duty.  The  mistake 
made  by  New  England  theologians  was  to  reduce  all  virtue 
to  an  exercise  of  Christian  love. 

{2)  Benevolence  in  itself  has  no  moral  character;  it  receives 
this  from  right  reason.  To  live  in  purity,  justice,  truth  and 
honesty  constitute  a  part  but  not  all  of  our  duty. 

[3)  Not  loving  simply,  but  a  certain  style  or  mode  of  loving 
is  our  duty.  Hence  Aristotle's  Golden  Mean  has  an  im- 
portant place  in  morals. 

III.  The  Law  of  Commotioe  Goodness. 

The  rational  soul,  or  ego,  feels  and  follows  this  law  intui- 
tively ;  it  has  no  necessary  conception  of  the  law  above  it. 
Some  say  we  should  love  beings  according  to  their  dignity ; 
it  is  true  that  we  should  have  a  special  love  for  morally 
excellent  beings,  but  this  cannot  be  said  to  be  an  exercise  of 
affectional  goodness. 

The  Law  of  Com  motive  Goodness  inquires  consentaneity  of 
ja^eciion  with  Practive  Goodness — one  should  exercise  love  to 
others  consentaneously  with  doing  them  good. 


28 

(i)  So  as  not  to  conflict  with  other  duty — never  love  man 
more  than  God. 

(^)  So  as  to  give  assistance  and  cooperation — thus  we  should 
live,  with  special  love  to  our  neighbor,  to  whom  we  may  do 
more  good  than  to  people  at  a  distance. 

{3)  When  these  regulations  are  observed  there  arises  a  call 
for  a  free  exercise  of  affection  to  all  beings.  In  this  way 
God  loves  all  who  are  capable  of  being  loved. 

IV.  Reasons  for  this  rule  are  in  the  rule  itself  but  may  be 
more  distinctly  considered.  To  secure  {a)  a  unity  or  har- 
mony of  man's  life  as  an  active  moral  being ;  (b)  to  reinforce 
Practive  Goodness ;  (c)  to  realize  in  right-loving  itself  one  of 
the  highest  and  most  absolute  of  good  things. 


LECTURE  XII. 


Practive  Goodness  enjoins  us  to  do  all  the  good  that  the  case 
admits  of.  Commotive  goodness  follows  the  same  law.  We 
should  love  as  many  beings  as  possible,  and  as  much  as  may 
be.  Regulative  Righteousness  is  a  law  allied  to  Moral 
Goodness.  The  term  Regulative  Righteousness  may  have 
a  very  wide  signification.  General  Righteousness  may 
comprehend  all  duty,  including  Moral  Goodness  and  Moral 
Ethics.  So  the  theologians  of  the  Middle  Ages  spoke  of 
justitia  toia. 

Reg-ulative  Righteousness. 

I.  But  commonly,  and  as  now  used,  the  terms  Righteous- 
ness and  Justice  have  a  more  restricted  sense.  Righteous- 
ness, as  we  now  employ  it,  does  not  cover  the  whole  of  the 
moral  law,  but  designates  that  morality  which  regulates  life 
by  rules,  rather  than  guides  life  by  positive  aims.  But  we 
must  not  limit  Righteousness  too  much.  Civil  law  enforces 
only  rules  of  Righteousness,  but  the  rules  of  Righteousness  are 


29 

not  alHneluded  in  civil  law,  since  it  embraces  much  more. 
A  great  heresy  was  introduced  by  Thomas  Hobbes  when  he 
claimed  that  the  right  was  fixed  by  the  will  of  the  sovereign 
and  by  civil  authority.  There  are  many  things  which  are  just 
and  right  and  obligatory,  of  which  civil  law  takes  no  notice. 
Thus  the  laws  of  Regulative  Righteousnes  are  fashioned  by 
the  moral  sense — the  conscience.  When  we  compare  Regu- 
lative Righteousness ,  and  Moral  Goodness,  one  gives  us 
aims  and  the  other  give^ys  rules. ^ 

II.  Since  the  rules  of  Righteousness  and  aims  of  Good- 
ness are  both  alike  right  and  obligatory,  we  naturally  look 
for  a  common  basis  for  this  in  both.  The  laws  of  Righteous- 
ness are  many  and  diverse;  the  aims  of  gjoodness  are  essen- 
tially one.  In  all  our  moral  aims  and  hopes,  we  want  only 
the_^q^  of  men.  If  there  be  anything  common,  it  must  be 
related  to  the  general  end  of  goodness. 

Analyzing  the  laws  of  Righteousness,  we  find  each  really 
concerns  a  general  good  or  interest.  I^otice  the  four  principal 
classes  in  the  decalogue  of  man's  relations  to  his  fellow  men: 

(i)  Obey  superiors — fifth  commandment. 

(2)  Do  not  kill — cause  no  bodily  harm  to  any  one. 

(3)  Do  not  commit  adultery — a  chaste  and  pure  life. 
{4)  Do  not  steal — rights  of  property  sacred. 

(5)  Or  bear  false-witness — truth  or  veracity  always. 

Going  over  these  again,  we  see  the  great  and  radical 
interest  involved  in  each  : 

{1)  Obedience — without  this  the  home  would  be  broken 
up.     Even  the  state  could  not  exist  without  obedience. 

(3)  Cruelty  is  abhorrent  to  us,  everywhere.  Necessity, 
alone,  can  justify  the  taking  away  of  life. 

(<?)  family  relations  must  be  conserved  or  the  world  will 
be  simply  the  dwelling-place  of  brutes  and  animals. 

(4)  Man  has  a  right  to  become  rich  and  prosperous. 

(5)  At  first  sight  this  appears  separate  from  men's  inter- 
ests, on  the  ground  that  we  should  tell  the  truth  always. 
But  truth  is  one  of  the  most  fundamental  and  vital  interests 
of  mankind. 


30 

The  affectional  rules  of  Righteousness  follow  the  practical 
rules  in  much  the  same  way  that  the  duty  of  loving  follows 
the  duty  of  doing  good.  They  agree  in  one  respect :  they 
both  relate  to  good.  They  are  contrasted :  one  is  progres- 
sive, the  other  conservative. 

III.  Regulative  Righteousness  is  defensive  and  conserva- 
tive morality,  and  is  contrasted  with  goodness  as  not  being 
essentially  progressive.  We  should  not  only  refrain  from 
evil  but  should  also  conserve  the  good.  Some  have  called 
Moral  Goodness  a  positive  virtue,  and  Righteousness  a  nega- 
tive virtue.  But  a  rule  of  Regulative  Righteousness  is  like  a 
railroad  bridge :  does  not  contribute  directly  to  our  onward 
progress,  but  yet  performs  a  part. 

This  conservativeness  is  its  radical  essence,  but  it  has  a 
positive  bearing.  Its  rules  or  modes  of  action  are  not  so  im- 
mediately and  evidently  connected  with  their  ends  or  results 
as  those  of  Moral  Goodness.  Hence,  there  is  sometimes  a 
tendency  to  break  loose  from  right  rules  and  seek  ends  at 
variance  with  Regulative  Righteousness.  Veracity — duty  of 
giving  truth  to  those  who  have  the  right  to  know  the  truth. 

IV.  Yet,  in  every  case,  they  not  only  defend  or  conserve 
some  good,  but  also  some  absolute  good.  Thus,  the  idea  of 
absolute  good  or  absoluteness  of  good,  directly  or  indirectly, 
seems  to  shape  the  laws  of  Practive  Goodness,  of  Commotive 
Goodness,  and  of  Regulative  Righteousness. 


LECTURE  XIII. 

Causative  Righteousness. 


We  pass  over  Moral  Esteem,  in  its  two  developments, 
practical  and  affectional,  remarking  only  that  neither  of  these 
conflicts  with  the  law  of  Moral  Goodness,  but,  like  that  law, 
and  like  the  law  of  Regulative  Righteousness,  they  have 
their  basis  in  the  conception  of  absolute  good. 


31 

I.  Causative  Righteousness  has  two  forms — the  inci'Dm^f.  and 
thejkmlojaed.  The  first  aims  chieflj  to  stimulate  virtue  ^wA 
make  it  effective.  Just  as  in  dangers,  we  stimulate  the 
courage  of  men  by  earnest  words.  The  second  promotes 
virtue,  as  in  itself  a  great  and  excellent  end.  Just  as  we 
seek  education,  not  for  what  we  may  remember,  but  that  we 
may  grow  into  true  and  honorable  men. 

II.  Virtue  as  formally  an  end  has  been  called  Moral  Good. 
Moral  Good  aims  at  good  in  its  practical  and  affectional 

forms ;  Regulative  Righteousness  aims,  not  so  positively,  but 
still  at  good ;  the  aims  of  Moral  Esteem  coincide  with  those 
of  Moral  Goodness  and  add  to  the  sum  of  good  and  the 
happiness  of  rational  beings. 

THUS  VIRTUE  IS  A  GOOD  : 

[1)  By  reason  of  its  direct  operation  to  ham'sh^verv  form  of 
evil  doing  jiudi  to  realize  beneficence  and  righteousness.  It 
aims  at  the  welfare  and  blessedness  of  human  beings,  and  if 
it  had  its  scope  the  millennium  would  soon  be  here. 

(^)  By  reason  of  its  concomitants  Virtue  is  the  proper,  ob- 
ject of  a  pure  and  high  spiritual  life.  Its  qualities  make  it 
the  })r()per  object  of  our  admiration  and  affection.  These 
are  [a)  its  inherent,  beauty  and  loveliness,  of  which  the  char- 
acter of  Christ  gives  us  the  most  conspicuous  example. 
(6)  The  well  ordered  condition  both  of  inward  capacity  and 
external  relation  which  the  virtuous  enjoy.  It  is  the  way  of 
true  and  eternal  prosperity.  In  virtue  man  obtains  more 
peace  and  happiness  than  anywhere  else,  (e)  The  inward 
and  constant  satisfaction  which  the  virtuous  spirit  experi- 
ences from  his  harmony  with  right  and  with  moral  order. 
That  a  peaceful  and  happy  frame  of  mind  can  only  be 
enjoyed  by  him  whose  heart  and  life  are  in  conformity  with 
moral  law,  is  not  a  doctrine  of  Scripture  alone,  but  the 
experience  of  all  people.  It  is  the  glory  of  our  gospel  to 
produce  this  virtue  in  its  fullness. 


32 

III.  Virtue  is  the  purest,  greatest  and  best  good — thB^ummum 
Bonum.  It  enters  into  the  human  soul  and  becomes  a 
fountain  of  eternal  life.  As  such,  it  is  the  highest  form  of 
Absolute  Good.  We  dutifully  promote  virtue  under  this 
aspect  of  it.  Hence  the  absurdity  of  "  Do  evil  that  good 
may  come."  We  should  do  nothing  accompanied  by  moral 
turpitude. 

IV.  Absolute  Good  is  the  highest  and  broadest  practical 
conception  of  the  human  mind.  But,  as  Dr.  McCosh  re- 
marks, regarding  the  phrase  Moral  Good  :  "  the  word  good 
here,  but  feebly  expresses  our  thought,  because  ordinarily 
good  refers  to  what  is  merely  useful  or  pleasurable."  The 
TO  (iya-d^ov  of  Plato  scems  to  have  been  his  expression  for 
Absolute  Good.  It  included  every  right  ethical  end,  and  em- 
braced every  divine  excellence.  Absolute  Good,  as  an  end, 
is  the  matter  of  the  Moral  Law. 


LECTURE  XIV. 

Conclusion. 


We  have  reached  the  idea  of  ro  ayadnv^  or  absolute  good,  as 
the  ultimate  form  of  the  moral  law.  The  doctrine  of  ru  ciyad-ov 
consists  with  the  common  conviction  of  mankind,  we  identify  the 
right  with  absolute  good  as  o.n  end  and  moral  rightness  with  abso- 
luteness of  good  as  characterizing  an  end.  It  has  been  the 
habit  of  philosophers  merely  to  meditate  on  duty  and  moral 
law,  and  then  to  endeavor  to  obtain  a  principle  which  may 
pervade  and  explain  it  all.  Our  doctrine  has  not  been 
reached  by  conjecture ;  not  by  the  comparison  of  theories,  as  is 
the  case  with  Cicero  and  Aristotle ;  not  by  deduction  from 
general  principles.  To  reason  here  from  general  principles 
is  to  fall  into  petitio  principii.  We  must  form  general  princi- 
ples and  not  reason  from  them.    The  doctrine  is  reached  by 


patient  analysis  and  generalization.  Moral  rightuess  is  the 
absoluteness  of  good  of  the  absolutely  good;  having  this 
absoluteness  as  an  end,  it  has  the  attribute  of  rightness. 

Does  it  conform  to  the  Common  Sense  of  men  f  If  it  disagrees 
Avith  any  of  the  phenomena  which  it  is  offered  to  explain,  it 
is  unsatisfactory. 

We  consider  absolute  good  to  be  the  basis  of  moral  law. 

I.  It  accounts  for  that  peculiar  excellence  and  attractive- 
ness which  belongs  to  right  ends  and  actions.  For  the  law 
is  holy,  just  and  good'. 

The  moral  law  has  its  goodness  to  a  great  extent  in  being 
holy  and  just.  Holiness  is  goodness  considered  in  opposition 
to  everything  evil  and  wrong. 

Then  justice  is  a  kind  of  deliberate  and  thoughtful  good- 
ness, according  to  which  we  defend  the  most  important  inter- 
ests of  rational  beings. 

Absolute  goodness  is  at  the  bottom  of  the  attractiveness 
which  philosophers  and  poets  ascribe  to  virtue,  e.g.,  the 
choice  of  Hercules. 

II.  It  explains  the  legal  superiority  and  supremacy  of 
right  ends  and  modes  of  conduct  over  all  others  which  can 
in  any  way  compete  with  them.  "I  would  rather  be  right 
than  President."  "Duty  should  be  first  and  pleasure  after- 
wards." Every  other  pursuit  besides  pleasure  should  be  sub- 
ordinated to  right  and  duty.  For  the  absolute  good,  in  any 
case,  is  the  total  amount  of  good  of  which  the  case  admits. 

In  divorce  laws,  incompatibility  of  temper  as  a  ground  of 
separation  would  result  in  untold  evils,  destroying  the  sta- 
bility of  society.  Special  and  private  must  be  subordinated 
to  absolute  good. 

III.  It  reveals  the  nature  of  moral  obligation,  i.e..,  of  the 
legal  subjection  of  one's  personal  life  to  the  claims  of  what 
is  right  and  good.  This  relation  is  sui  generis,  but  imme- 
diately follows  from  the  innate  superiority  of  all  forms  of  the 
ro  ayaUirj  Qvcr  all  Other  aims  or  ends.    The  relation  is  peculiar, 

3 


34 

like  that  of  similarity  or  the  relation  of  cause  and  eflect. 
There  are  relations  which  may  exist  and  yet  may  be  legal 
relations  though  they  do  not  exist,  e.g.,  the  mountain  travel- 
ler. The  nature  of  the  obligation  arises  from  the  nature  of 
the  ends. 

Those  ends  which  are  supreme  are  necessarily  supreme 
over  man's  actions. 

IV.  It  shows  the  rational  ground  on  which  specific  laws 
of  duty  may  be  limited  or  set  aside  for  the  time.  De  con- 
tentione  honesti  et  utilis  is  a  chapter  in  the  De  Officiis  illustra- 
ting this.     For,  to  be  useful  is  a  duty. 

There  are  cases  where  what  seems  to  be  one  absolute 
rio^ht  interferes  and  sets  aside  another  absolute  riojht.  Noth- 
ing  is  more  necessary  in  the  science  of  casuistry  than  a  rule 
setting  forth  which  duty  should  supercede  another;  it  must 
be  founded  on  some  such  principle  as  -o  ayrv^ov. 

Life  and  liberty  are  inalienable  rights,  yet  there  are  cases 
where  these  rights  are  forfeited  by  transgressions  or  sacrificed 
to  duty. 

The  weaker  right  always  sets  forth  something  which  is 
an  absolute  good  in  ordinary  circumstances.  The  stronger 
is  of  the  same  nature  but  extends  more  deeply  and  widely. 

V.  It  gives  the  most  satisfactory  explanation  of  Punitive 
Justice. 

This  principle  shows  itself  in  the  natural  instinct  to  inflict 
evil  on  the  evil-doer,  and  more  formally  in  Courts  and  Laws 
and  Penalties;    also  in  the  doctrine  of  Future  Punishment. 

But  what  God  and  good  men  hate  is  sin  and  not  the  sinner. 
Even  eternal  punishment  is  employed  with  an  end  of  good- 
.ness.  It  is  founded  on  the  principle  that  it  is  better  for  one 
man  to  perish  rather  than  all  be  destroyed.  It  is  the  neces- 
sary means  of  maintaining  the  Moral  Law  and  the  moral 
stability  and  prosperity  of  Created  Beings. 


§  3-     DIVISIONS    OF    ETHICS. 

There  are  several  divisions  given  for  this  science.  Calder 
wood  has  used  a  common  one  in  his  book,  viz.:  (i)  the 
Psychology  in  Ethics;  (2)  the  Metaphysic  in  Ethics;  (3)  Ap- 
plied Ethics.  Another  common  division  is  twofold,  viz.  : 
(i)  Theoretical,  and  (2)  Practical,  Ethics.  This,  tho'  sound,  is 
open  to  objections  in  that  (i)  some  topics  {c.  g.  love)  have  to 
be  treated  in  both  parts  and  (2)  the  division  is  too  mechanical. 
The  aim  of  the  following  division  will  be  to  show  the  organic 
relations  of  the  parts  of  the  science. 

(i)  The  Categorical  Imperative.  Ought  is  the  dominant 
word  in  Ethics.  It  may  appear  in  two  forms,  vi.'^.  :  (i)  the 
whiclrend  one  ought  to  realize  (=  the  Good),  and  (2)  the  norm 
to  which  one  ought  to  conform  (=-  the  Right).  Under  it, 
therefore,  are  two  heads — the  Right  and  the  Good. 

(2)  The  Right  may  be  viewed  in  two  ways:  (i)  subject- 
ively as  seen  in  conduct  (  —  virtue) ;  (2)  objectively  as  seen  in 
a  code  (=  moral  law). 

The  moral  law  will  enjoin  duties  on  a  person  in  accord- 
ance to  the  relations  in  which  he  stands.  These  duties  are  of 
two  kinds — 

(1)  The  duties  which  a  person  owes  as  an  individual, 
irrespective  of  his  relations  to  others.  These  give  rise  to  the 
science  of  Individual  Ethics. 

(2)  The  duties  which  grow  out  of  the  relations  of  a  man 
with  his  fellowmen.  These  give  rise  to  the  science  of  Social 
Ethics. 

§  4.  The  Categorical  Imperative.  As  to  this  three  ques- 
tions arise  : 

(i)  Why  are  morals  founded  on  the  Categorical  Imperative? 

(2)  Why  are  they  not  founded  on  the  Right  ? 

(3)  Why  are  they  not  founded  on  the  Good  ? 

(t)  The  idea  of  the  Categorical  Imperative  corresponding 
to  the  idea  of  ought,  implies  that  human  conduct  is  subject  to 
a  command  and  that  other  motives  are  not  to  be  considered  in 
comparison  to  the  command.  Impulses  may  exist,  but  when 
they  conflict  with  the  idea  of  ought  they  should  be  at  once 
rejected.  There  may  be  moral  impulses  and  appetites.  Du- 
gald  Stuart  has  treated  of  these  and  of  the  manner  of  their 
development.     But  we  also  act  under  the  feeling  of  oughtness. 


The  question  as  to  whether  the  idea  oi  ought  is  ultimate  or 
not,  is  a  most  important  ethical  problem.  On  its  solution 
depends  the  question  as  to  whether  conduct  is  ruled  by  the 
idea  of  ought  or  by  the  rules  of  experience. 

If  ought  is  an  a  priori  idea  it  is  the  most  appropriate  start- 
ing point  for  the  science  of  Ethics:  for  it  divides  conduct  into 
obligatory  and  non  obligatory  and  rules  out  the  non-obligatory 
as  non  ethical. 

If  actions  cannot  be  commanded  the  whole  science  of  Eth- 
ics must  be  changed.  If  there  is  no  obligatory  morality,  the 
science  of  Ethics  has  to  do  either  with  the  way  men  act  now, 
or  with  the  generalization  of  experience  into  rules  to  guide 
conduct.  Thus  if  a  man  made  pleasure  the  end  of  life,  the 
Epicurean  would  teach  him  that  the  best  way  to  prolong 
enjoyment  would  be  to  avoid  extremes.  Or  if  he  were  per- 
suaded to  live  for  the  health  and  life  of  the  social  organism, 
Leslie  Stevens  could  give  him  good  advice.  He  would  say 
that  the  moral  law  expresses  the  conditions  necessary  to  the 
healthy  perpetuation  of  humanity.  But  the  humanity  preached 
would  be  advice  and  not  command. 

Whether  the  Categorical  Imperative  has  a  right  to  its 
place  or  not  is  a  question  that  we  must  discuss.  But  if  it  has 
a  place,  morality  must  be  based  on  it. 

(2)  Our  system  of  Ethics  should  not  be  founded  on  the 
idea  of  Right :  for  this  idea  implies  a  standard  by  which  con- 
duct is  to  be  judged.  It  is  predicable  of  an  action,  not  of  an 
agent.  The  prior  question  why  we  ought  to  do  right  shows 
that  the  idea  o^  ought  is  above  that  of  Right. 

(3)  We  should  not  found  our  system  of  Ethics  on  the  idea 
of  Good,  not  for  the  reason  given  by  Calderwood — that  good 
is  predicable  only  of  things — but  because  the  good  is  generally 
understood  to  mean  the  desirable  and  therefore  the  end  or 
final  cause  of  action.  We  always  have  some  purpose  in  life, 
and  when  we  have  answered  the  question  what  we  intend  to 
make  of  ourselves,  we  have  found  what  is  for  us  the  good.  It 
may  be  "  getting  on  in  life,"  or  usefulness,  or  success  in  our 
profession,  etc.  Again  we  should  not  make  the  Good  the 
basis  of  our  ethical  system  because  the  Good  may  have  two 
different  meanings.  It  may  mean  (i)  what  men  individually 
and  collectively  actually  desire ;  and  (2)  what  they  ought  to 
desire. 


Suppose  we  found  our  system  on  the  Summum  Bonum 
and  begin  by  defining  the  Good  as  what  men  ought  to  desire. 
It  is  clear  that  we  take  for  granted  the  word  ought.  If,  on  the 
other  hand,  we  define  the  Good  as  what  men  actually  desire, 
our  system  of  Ethics,  lacking  the  idea  of  obligation,  will  be 
merely  a  system  of  advices  using  only  the  hypothetical  im- 
perative. 

§  5.  (a)  The  question  now  arises,  "  What  is  moral  con- 
conduct?"      What  conduct  is  capable  of  moral  measurement? 

As  far  as  Ethics  regulates  conduct,  we  must  consider  con- 
duct moral.  But  all  conduct  is  not  ethical.  Therefore  there 
is  moral  and  non-moral  conduct.  Many  things  have  no  moral 
quality  in  them  except  in  relation  to  other  things. 

(b)  A  second  question  is,  "  What  conduct  is  worthy  of 
moral  approval  ?  " 

A  bad  act  is  the  subject  of  moral  measurement,  but  not  of 
moral  approval.  Again  the  giving  a  large  gift  to  a  benevolent 
institution  is  the  subject  of  our  approval.  Bat  this  approval 
is  to  us  not  necessarily  moral.  We  would  not  have  con- 
demned the  giver  if  he  had  not  given  the  money.  But  the 
man  himself  may  feel  moral  approval  for  the  act.  He  may 
view  it  from  a  moral  standpoint — feeling  that  he  ought  to  put 
his  money  to  the  best  use.  If  a  man  acts  as  he  feels  he  ought, 
his  conduct  is  right.  Whether  the  act  is  right  or  not  is 
another  matter.  But  all  this  only  leads  to  the  conclusion  that 
every  act  to  be  judged  as  morally  right  must  (i)  be  capable  of 
moral  measurement — must  be,  or  be  felt  to  be,  obligatory — 
and  must  (2)  be  performed  unaffected  by  non-moral  influences. 
Thus  the  man  who  does  not  lie  or  steal  merely  because  he 
fears  detection  is  not  acting  morally.  Kant  presents  this  very 
strongly.  He  says  that  duty  is  a  necessity  to  act  out  of 
respect  for  law.  Hence,  no  matter  how  pure  one's  motive  may 
be,  unless  he  feels  it  his  duty  so  to  do,  the  act  is  not  a  moral 
one.  One  may  feel  both  an  obligation  and  an  appetite  or  im- 
pulse. If  these  conflict,  the  idea  of  obligation  should  come  to 
the  front.  If  duty  and  interest  agree,  and  if  the  man  regards 
only  his  interest  his  act  is  not  worthy  of  moral  approval. 
Kant  goes  further.  He  says  that  if  a  man's  aim  by  nature  be 
honorable  and  the  bad  is  offensive  to  him,  if  such  a  man  fol- 
lows his  natural  instincts  in  action,  his  act  is  not  moral.  E.g. 
If  there  are  three  men,  one  of  whom  is  honest  because 
honesty  pays,  a  second  is  honest  because  honesty  is  right, 
and   a   third    is    honest    because    his    whole    nature    rebels 


against  dishonesty,  Kant  would  give  his  moral  approval  only 
to  the  second.  "  The  act  of  the  first  is,"  he  says,  "  not  moral 
— infra-moral,"  The  act  of  the  third  should  therefore  be 
supra- moral.  Kant  does  not  say  so,  but  he  says  that  ought- 
ness  is  a  quality  predicable  only  of  imperfect  moral  agents. 
We  cannot  agree  with  him  here.  Moral  beings  cannot  trans- 
cend the  morally  right.  If  inclination  and  obligation  coincide 
the  latter  should  nf)t  be  ruled  out,  the  act  should  be  regarded 
as  capable  of  moral  measurement. 

§  6.  The  idea  of  oughtness  has  been  assumed  above  to  be 
given  a  priori.  This  has  been  objected  to  and  we  must  dis- 
cuss the  question.  We  cannot  stop  with  the  idea  of  ought- 
ness as  ultimate,  but  must  ask  what  is  behind  it.  We  discuss, 
therefore,  three  topics  which  underlie  the  Categorical  Im- 
perative : 

(i)  Oughtness  as  a  physchological  fact. 

(2)  Metaphysical  aspect  of  oughtness. 

(3)  The  relations  of  oughtness  and  human  freedom. 
§  7.     Oughtness  as  a  psychological  fact. 

It  may  help  to  reconcile  us  to  the  old  intuitional  idea  of 
oughtness  if  we  observe  the  diversity  of  ideas  among  those 
who  deny  it. 

(i)  Those  who  maintain  that  there  is  no  legitimate  place 
for  the  idea  of  duty  or  oughtness  in  Ethics.  Thus  Schopen- 
hauer says  that  oughtness  is  only  a  superficial  and  vulgar 
idea  and  that  Ethics  is  only  theoretical :  that  the  principle  of 
good  arose  from  the  pity  men  have  for  each  other,  and  the 
principle  of  wrong,  from  the  insensibility  of  men  for  each 
other.  In  his  view  moral  science  would  describe  men  as 
Biology  does  animals. 

He  puts  sympathy  for  obligation  and  leads  to  conduct 
which  he  approves  but  does  not  command.  Yet  he  acknowl- 
edges that  only  moral  agents  can  be  commanded. 

Adam  Smith  makes  the  same  mistake  in  ignoring  oughtness. 

(2)  Those  who  claim  that  the  doctrine  of  moral  obligation 
rests  on  the  idea  of  will.  Thus  Hobbes  claims  that  no  right 
exists  until  a  law  is  enunciated  by  the  state.  Bain  reproduces 
this. 

The  difference  between  this  school  and  the  Intuitionists 
turns  on  the  relation  of  moral  law  to  obligation.  Hobbes  and 
his  school  consider  moral  law  and  conscience  as  the  product 
of  human  law.     The  Intuitionists  hold  the  contrary. 


■  ^\ 


r 


*^ 


■■ii^kmT^ 


'"^ 


%. 


i 


^ 


j^mh, 


%