Skip to main content

Full text of "Locke a constructive relativist"

See other formats


UC-NRLF 


B 

2. 

H3 


MS    23M 


CO 


LOCKE  A  CONSTRUCTIVE 
RELATIVIST 


HENRY  GL  HARTMANN 

&)iitf1imt'   lecturer  in    Philosophy  at   ColumMa    Un-ive.rxity 


A  Dissertation  submitted  in  partial  fulfillment  of  the  require- 
ments for  the  Degree  of  Doctor  of  Philosophy  in  the  Faculty 
of  Philosophy,  Columbia  University. 


NEW    YORK 

1912 


LOCKE  A  CONSTRUCTIVE 
RELATIVIST 


BY 


HENRY  G.  HARTMANN 

Sometime  Lecturer  in  Philosophy  at  Columbia   University 


A  Dissertation  submitted  in  partial  fulfillment  of  the  require- 
ments for  the  Degree  of  Doctor  of  Philosophy  in  the  Faculty 
of  Philosophy,  Columbia  University. 


NEW    YORK 

1912 


8123*7 


INTRODUCTION 


IN  presenting  Locke  as  a  Constructive  Relativist  I  claim  to 
present  him  in  his  central  and  most  inclusive  doctrine.  It  is  not 
the  view  I  held  of  Locke  a  short  time  ago.  Nor  is  it  likely  that 
my  older  conception  of  him  would  have  undergone  its  radical 
change,  if  it  had  not  been  for  the  fact  that  conditions  led  me  to 
give  Book  III  of  his  Essay  more  serious  reading  than  our  traditional 
opinion  of  it  seemed  to  invite. 

Locke  tells  his  friend  Molyneux  that  Book  III  gave  him  more 
labor  in  the  writing  than  the  rest  of  the  Essay.  This  fact  does  not 
of  necessity  insure  merit.  Yet  I  mention  it  as  a  fact  not  without 
its  significance,  and,  in  addition,  venture  the  further  statement, 
that,  until  Book  III  was  written,  Locke  never  came  into  full  pos- 
session of  his  "  new  way  of  ideas  " — a  way  that  not  only  yields  what 
is  most  distinctive  in  modern  pragmatism,  but  its  much-lacking,  or 
relevant,  metaphysics  as  well.  I  admit  Book  III  does  not  at  first 
appear  to  have  its  specific  doctrines  writ  in  italics.  Locke  himself 
confesses  in  respect  to  this  Book :  "  I  should  not  much  wonder  if 
there  be  in  some  places  of  it  obscurity  and  doubtfulness  .  .  . 
though  the  thoughts  were  easy  and  clear  enough,  yet  (it)  cost  me 
more  pains  to  express  them  than  all  the  rest  of  my  Essay."  The 
fact  is  that  Locke's  "  new  way  of  ideas  "  here  took  its  last  "  new  " 
turn,  and  its  consummate  character  once  clearly  grasped,,  one 
ceases  over  night  to  view  Locke  traditionally. 

In  affirming  Locke  to  be  essentially  the  constructive  relativist 
and  not  essentially  the  reputed  sensationalist,  I  expose  myself  to 
misunderstanding.  He  is  the  sensationalist,  as  reputed,  for  those 
who  will  not  consider  Locke  beyond  the  evident  sensationalistic 
implications  of  his  doctrine,  and  who,  in  support  of  their  claim, 
may  turn  to  the  British  movement  in  philosophy  that  rose  out  of 
it.  But  let  it  be  remembered  that  Kant's  philosophy  also  had  an 
origin  in  Locke,  and  do  I  trespass  in  stating  that  perhaps  Prag- 
matism owes  more  to  Locke  than  may  be  consciously  recognized  or 

3 

254199 


accepted.  So  historical  outcome  pitted  against  historical  outcome 
avails  little  in  deciding  an  issue. 

In  denying  Locke  to  be  primarily  the  sensationalist,  I  am  not 
unaware  that  T.  H.  Green  (not  to  mention  others)  has  written  a 
critique  of  him  that  dare  not  be  ignored.  His  aim,  however,  is  to 
show  up  Locke  negatively,  not  positively;  to  show  him  up  in  the 
light  of  a  sensationalistic  exponent,  and,  further,  to  show  him  up 
in  all  the  absurdities  to  which  all  departure  in  Locke  from  this 
principle  and  Green's  self-imposed  dialectics,  would,  in  addition, 
naturally  commit  him.  This  sort  of  criticism  is  not  helpful,  how- 
ever else  remarkable  the  critique  may  be  in  its  superior  merits  and 
mental  acrobatics. 

To  begin  with,  instead  of  finding  Locke  abandoning  "  the  his- 
torical plain  method,"  to  which  he  pledges  himself  in  his  Intro- 
duction, in  order  to  pursue  the  psychological  trend,  of  which  he 
stands  accused,  I  find  him  in  the  main  so  consistent  with  his  orig- 
inal design  that  I  am  almost  inclined  to  ignore  the  first  half  dozen 
or  more  of  his  chapters  in  Book  II  for  the  havoc  they  have  done 
in  distorting,  or  rather  eclipsing,  the  far  more  -central,  consistent, 
and  evolved  doctrine  existing  in  his  pages.  And  when,  in  addition, 
I  find  Locke  expressly  acknowledging  his  departure  from  the 
avowed  method  whenever,  in  his  psychological  digressions,  the 
departure  occurs,  I  ask  myself  what  blame  for  all  this  distortion 
of  our  perspective  rests  with  Berkeley  and  Hume?  There  is  no 
need,  however,  for  all  that  to  lessen  the  value  of  the  chapters  indi- 
cated. Chapter  VIII  of  that  Book,  in  particular,  is  not  the  only 
instance  where  we  find  Locke  forcing  an  extreme  view :  and,  hence, 
discounting  the  exaggeration  of  his  views  in  this  chapter  is  not  any 
more,  nor  any  less,  valid,  than  to  do  so  with  the  many  other  extreme 
views  with  which  his  Essay  abound.  Read  him  where  we  will,  we 
find,  as  I  shall  endeavor  to  outline,  the  most  one-sided  and  extreme 
position  brought  face  to  face  in  his  pages  with  others  equally 
extreme  and  one-sided;  and  when  we  ask  where  in  this  jumble  of 
views  we  are  to  find  Locke,  it  behooves  us  to  arrest  any  tendency  to 
frame  a  too  hasty  judgment  concerning  the  matter,  and,  most  of 
all,  at  the  outset,  to  venture  the  assumption  that  Locke  did  not 
know  his  own  mind.  It  requires  no  great  discernment  to  perceive 
that  Green  got  his  guiding  thread,  not  from  Locke  himself,  but 
from  the  traditional  view  of  him.  But  Locke  remains  Locke, 
work  the  veritable  gold  mine  of  his  Essay  for  some  of  its  gold  only, 
or  for  most  of  it,  or  merely  for  its  dross. 

The  whole  matter  hinges  upon  the  role  of  the  simple  ideas. 


5' 

Are  they  at  bottom  to  be  taken  as  working  assumptions  or  as  actual 
facts?  Here  Locke  himself  vacillates  although  tradition  does  not. 
"  The  historical  plain  method,"  in  its  application,  has  one  specific 
problem  set:  the  problem  of  the  One  and  the  Many,  in  the  solu- 
tion of  which,  his  simple  ideas  (namely,  his  sensationalism)  are 
not  a  problem  but  assumed  facts,  even  though  at  times  he  is 
strongly  disposed  to  make  and  consider  them  as  more.  When  he 
inclines  to  consider  them  as  more  than  assumptions,  he,  with  con- 
fession, ceases  to  be  the  metaphysician  and  turns  psychologist,  and 
then  the  simple  ideas  themselves  becomes  a  problem,  and  no  longer 
the  merely  descriptive  assumptions.  Yet  he  writes :  "  Every  mixed 
mode,  consisting  of  many  distinct  simple  ideas,  it  seems  reasonable 
to  inquire,  '  whence  it  has  its  unity,  and  how  such  a  precise  multi- 
tude comes  to  make  but  one  idea,  since  that  combination  does  not 
always  exist  together  in  nature  ? '  To  which  I  answer,  it  is  plain 
it  has  its  unity  from  an  act  of  the  mind."  x  Whether  his  simple 
ideas  are  in  fact  simple  or  whether  complex,  the  problem  upper- 
most with  him,  notwithstanding,  would  persist:  "how  such  a 
precise  multitude  comes  to  make  but  one  idea."  For  we  do  regard 
charity  as  one  idea,  however  multitudinous  its  parts,  and  so  with 
our  notions  of  man  or  gold.  They  have  no  unity  actually  existing 
"  in  nature  " ;  then  "  whence  do  they  have  their  unity  ?  "  The 
sensationalistic  interpretation  of  Locke  would  imply  that  the 
simple  ideas  rather  than  the  complex  ideas  engrossed  his  interest. 
I  venture  the  opposite  contention.  Sensationalism  in  Locke  is  but 
a  subordinate  phase  or  part  of  his  constructive  relativity.  Nor  is 
any  student  of  Locke  in  a  position  to  decide  the  issue  unless  he 
too  has  gotten  beyond  the  traditional  habit  of  neglecting  Book  III. 

1.  Bk.  II,  ch.  22,  sec.  4. 


CONTENTS 

PAGE 
Introduction     3 

I 
GENEEAL   SURVEY 

CHATTER 

I.     The  Two  Fundamental  Steps  in  Locke's  Philosophy 9 

II.     Relativity   Defined    and   Locke's    Position    Indicated    in   Respect 

to    its  Various   Formulations 16 

II 
RELATIVISTIC   MOTIVES   IN    LOCKE 

III.  The  Simple  Ideas :     What  Are  They? 21 

I  V.  The   Part-Whole    Motive 26 

V.  The  Term-Relation  Motive 30 

V  I .  Locke  's   Conception   of  Relation 37 

III 
ANTI-RELATIVISTIC    MOTIVES    IN    LOCKE 

VII.     Ideas  Versus  Knowledge  and  Meaning 43 

VIII.     Absolute  Knowledge :    The  Primacy  of  the  ' '  Invisible  Relation ' ' 

and  of  Conduct 48 

IV 
CONSTRUCTIVE   RELATIVITY  IN  LOCKE 

IX.     Doctrine  of  Sorts:    Mixed  Modes  and  Substances 60 

X.     Doctrine  of  Meaning  (' '  Ideas  of  Relation  ") 76 

XL     Conclusion     88 

7 


'- 


GENERAL  SURVEY 
CHAPTER  I 

THE  TWO   FFXDAMEXTAL  STEPS  IN"  LOCKERS  PHILOSOPHY 

ee  IT  is  past  doubt,"  says  Locke,  "  that  men  have  in  their  minds 
several  ideas, — such  as  are  those  expressed  by  the  words  whiteness, 
hardness,  sweetness,  thinking,  motion,  man,  elephant,  army,  drunk- 
enness, and  others :  it  is  in  the  first  place  then  to  be  inquired, — How 
he  comes  by  them  ? "*  Locke's  position  here  is  clear.  He  takes 
existing  distinctions  in  consciousness  as  the  starting-point  in  his 
ill  1  ompted  "  account  of  the  ways  whereby  our  understandings  come 
to  attain  these  notions  of  things  we  have."2  This  position  cannot 
be  overemphasized.  He  accepts  the  reality  of  thinking  and  the 
reality  of  distinctions  within  thought,  and  his  sole  problem  is,  not 
whether  such  distinctions  exist  apart  from  thought,  nor  what  they 
may  chance  to  be  apart  from  thought,  but  how  such  distinctions, 
as  commonly  recognized  in  our  experience,  come  about;  what  is 
their  ground  or  basis?  And  it  is  my  contention  that  this  problem 
in  Locke  gets  its  most  specific  and  most  evolved  solution  in  his 
doctrine  of  Sorts  in  Book  III. 

His  first  general  attempt  to  account  for  such  distinctions  con- 
sists in  his  contention,  that  all  we  know  of  reality  resolves  itself  ^ 
into  ideas,  of  which  he  recognizes  two  sorts, — simple  ideas  and  com- 
plex ideas.  Of  these,  simple  ideas  are  ultimate  and  underived; 
the  complex  ideas  a  mere  aggregation  of  the  simple  ideas.  Knowl- 
edge, in  Locke's  sense  of  the  word,  is  in  no  way  involved  in  the 
conscious  existence  of  simple  ideas,  although  the  organism  is 
involved  in  the  production  of  some  of  them  (the  secondary  quali- 

1.  Bk.  II,  eh.  1,  sec.  1. 

2.  Introduction,  sec.  2. 


10 

ties).  Knowledge  begins  its  career  only  when  the  simple  ideas 
are  brought  into  union  or  connection  by  the  mind,  and  terminates 
in  such  products  as  (1)  Complex  Ideas,  (2)  Meaning,  (3)  Knowl- 
edge proper,  and  (4)  Knowledge  as  opinion  or  judgments  of  prob- 
ability. All  these  evolved  distinctions  within  our  experience,  so 
Locke  contends,  are,  notwithstanding,  but  complications  or  modes 
of  simple  ideas,  and  that  they  approximate  reality  so  far  only  as 
they  admit  of  a  reduction  to  their  source  of  origin  in  the  simple 
ideas.  Hence  that  contention  in  Locke,  that  complex  ideas  and 
meaning,  considered  apart  from  their  reduction  to  simple  ideas, 
are  unreal,  and  that  knowledge  in  general  is  unreal  and  irrelevant, 
except  where  grounded  in  the  necessity  of  a  "  visible  and  neces- 
sary" relation  between  them;  that  is,  that  knowledge  remains 
unreal  until,  as  a  perceptive  meaning,  as  it  were,  it  resolves  itself  to 
the  status  of  a  simple  irreducible  idea.  Here  the  principle  that 
comes  to  the  surface  is,  that  what  is  rational  is  real,  in  conformity 
with  which,  Locke  makes  the  a  priori  modes  the  highest  and  most 
perfect  forms  of  reality.  But  the  simple  ideas,  on  the  other  hand, 
are  also  made  the  supreme  forms  of  reality.  From  this  it  would 
follow  that  there  are  two  principles  of  truth  and  reality  recognized 
by  Locke,  and  not  one,  although  now  it  is  the  one  that  gains  the 
ascendancy  in  him,  and  then  the  other.  But  even  when  ignoring 
this  dual  standard  and  confining  ourselves  to  the  empirical  standard 
only,  we  find  the  same  see-saw  manifested  in  his  pages.  In  different 
parts  of  his  Essay,  he  evaluates  complex  ideas  and  meaning  very 
differently  in  respect  to  simple  ideas,  by  hypothesis,  considered  the 
sole  ultimates.  We  find  that  complex  ideas  and  meaning  get  them- 
selves viewed,  now  as  unreal,  then  as  real, — as  real  and  as  ultimate 
as  his  hypothetical  simple  ideas.  And  when  we  ask  by  Avhieh 
decision  Locke  in  truth  stands,  we  can  answer  in  the  affirmative, 
one  way  or  the  other,  only  by  emphasizing  his  statements  at  one 
place  and  in  one  context,  and  by  ignoring  what  he  as  explicitly 
states  to  the  contrary  in  other  parts  of  his  Essay.  He  who  does  not 
take  these  various  contradictions  in  Locke  in  full  consideration,  and 
hold  them  together,  may  attain  to  a  consistent  theory  or  view  in 
him,  but  he  can  do  so  only  by  a  process  of  elimination  and  by  a  sub- 
stitution of  a  dialect,  so  to  speak,  for  Locke's  own  rich,  although 
varied,  utterance.  It  is  as  difficult  at  times  to  answer  whether 
Locke  is  a  rationalist  as  it  is  to  answer  whether  Locke  i.-  an 
empiricist;  just  as  upon  the  empirical  basis,  as  just  indicated,  it 
is  difficult  at  times  to  answer  whether  Locke  regards  meaning 
and  complex  ideas  as  ultimate  as  simple  ideas,  or  not.  What  are 


11 

we  to  make  of  this  tangle?    At  what  point  dogmatise  concerning 
him? 

Locke's  first  step,  as  iust  stated,  "  to  account  for  the  ways 
whereby  our  understandings  come  to  attain  those  notions  oi  thinffiL 
we  havej!  led  him  to  the  helief  that  simple  ideas  contained  the 
sole  ground  of  explanation.  He  rests  his  claim  upon  the  fact  that 
the  simple  ideas  are  essentially  non-relative.  To  admit  anything 
else  were  to  court  an  infinite  regress — such  seems  his  conviction. 
Yet,  on  the  other  hand,  he  admits  as  emphatically,  (1)  that  they 
are  conditioned  in  their  shape  and  character  by  the  structure  of  our 
sense  organs;  (2)  that,  within  such  existing  structure,  variation 
in  range  and  acuteness  of  perception  is  the  law;  (3)  that  their 
perception  by  a  direct  vision,  involving  a  transcendence  of  the 
ordinary  mode  of  perception,  is  ideal ;  (4)  that  they  involve  a  latent 
judgment;  (5)  that  they  reduce  to  mere  products  of  externally  con- 
ditioning factors  (relativity)  ;  (6)  that  simple  modes,  although 
complex,  are  irreducible;  (7)  that  complex  modes  arc  ultimate 
and  have  their  real  essence  in  thought (  a  priori  rationalism)  ;  (8) 
that  complex  ideas  of  substances  are  ultimate  and  have  their  reality 
in  distinctions  as  final  in  character  as  our  distinction  between  a 
horse  and  a  stone.  And  thus  he  wrestles  with  his  problem  to 
and  fro !  Simple  ideas  are  ultimate — this  conclusion  he  will  not 
let  go,  and  yet  he  feels  himself  forced  to  admit ;  u  that  whatever 
doth  or  can  exist,  or  be  considered  as  one  thing,  is  positive ;  and  so 
not  only  simple  ideas  and  substances,  but  modes  also,  arc  positive 
beings ;  though  the  parts  of  which  they  consist  are  very  often  rel- 
ative one  to  another;  but  the  whole  together,  considered  as  one 
thing,  and  producing  in  us  the  complex  idea  of  one  thing,  which 
idea  is  in  our  minds,  as  one  picture  though  an  aggregate  of  divers 
parts,  is  a  positive  or  absolute  thing  or  idea."  3  But  if  simple  ideas, 
by  the  admissions  catalogued,  are  conceded  to  be  complex  or  rel- 
ative, as  the  case  may  be,  and  complex  ideas,  as  just  quoted,  "  pos- 
itive or  absolute,"  what  becomes  of  our  original  and  fundamental 
distinction  between  simple  ideas  and  our  complex  ideas?  The 
next  quotation  will  aid  to  a  solution  of  the  matter  in  Locke's  own 
words.  "  It  is  not,  therefore,  unity  of  substance,"  writes  Locke  in 
his  chapter  on  Identity  and  Diversity,  "  that  Comprehends  all 
sort  of  identity,  or  will  determine  it  in  every  case.  .  .  .  Thus  in 
the  case  of  living  creatures,  their  identity  depends,  not  on  a  mass 
of  particles,  but  on  something  else."4  But  what  is  this  something 

3.  Bk.  II,  ch.  25,  sec.  6. 

4.  Bk.  II,  sec.  7. 


12 

else,  capable  of  conferring  a  unity  where  there  is  a  diversity? 
Our  answer  to  this  question  conducts  us  into  the  second  funda- 
mental step  in  Locke's  philosophy,  and  it  consists  in  locating  the 
principle  of  unit}7  in  the  subject  and  no  longer  in  any  external 
object.  In  Book  IV  this  principle  is  located  in  "  Reason  " ;  in 
Book  III  it  is  located  in  what  he  terms  an  abstract  idea  or  defini- 
tion :  in  Book  II  in  what  he  terms  "  ideas  of  relations " ;  and, 
lastly,  throughout  his  Essay,  in  what  he  frequently  terms  "  our 
happiness  or  misery,  beyond  which  we  have  no  concernment,  either 
of  knowing  or  being."  5  Even  our  simple  ideas  do  not  escape 
this  general  transfer  in  their  unity,  and,  in  their  case,  found  in 
the  particular  character  and  structure  of  our  sense  organs,  or  in 
a  single  picture  or  conception  in  the  mind.  The  outcome  of  the 
doctrine,  taken  in  its  full  setting,  is  what  I  term  constructive 
relativity. 

His  treatment  of  this  general  subject  is  critical  and  destructive, 
as  well  as  positive  and  constructive.  A  general  outline  of  his 
inquiry,  with  a  suggestion  of  the  final  conclusion  to  be  reached, 
will  amply  suffice  for  a  passing  orientation  in  this  second  and 
more  fundamental  step  in  Locke's  philosophy. 

Our  simple  ideas  given,  why  not  rest  content  with  them?  Why 
seek  to  combine  them  ?  And  when  we  thus  set  about  to  unite  them, 
what  constitutes  our  motive  or  motives,  and  what  our  "  patterns  "  ? 
Grant,  if  you  will,  that  a  certain  aim  is  compassed  in  reducing 
complex  ideas  to  simple  ideas,  whether  that  aim  be  pragmatic  (a 
test  of  their  truth  or  reality)  or  epistemological  (a  determination 
of  the  varied  elements  involved  in  a  possible  bit  of  knowledge,  or 
in  knowledge  as  a  whole),  and  }ret  it  is  evident  that  no  adequate 
"  account  of  the  ways  whereby  our  understandings  come  to  attain 
those  notions  of  things  we  have  "  could  halt  with  the  fact  that  our 
particular  notions  involve  a  purely  general  reality,  a  purely  general 
truth,  and  a  purely  general  meaning;  it  is  well-nigh  tantamount  to 
saying  that  they  have  no  reality,  truth,  or  meaning  at  all.  The 
emphasis  with  Locke  throughout  finds  itself  placed,  not  upon  the 
universal,  but  upon  the  particulars.  Hence  his  real  problem :  sim- 
ple ideas  given,  why  do  we  combine  them  at  all,  and  such  and 
such  qualities  with  this  object,  and  others  with  other  objects?  We 
may  seek  the  solution  in  the  answer,  that  different  objects  are 
inherently  of  a  different  constitution  or  essence.  But  this  answer 
merely  begs  the  question  at  issue.  We  answer  our  question  by 
off-hand  asserting  a  principle  of  differentiation  not  discoverable 
5.  Bk.  IV,  eh.  11,  sec.  8. 


13 

within  our  experience.  Now  Locke  vigorously  denies  the  validity 
thus  to  explain  our  why.  Thus  he  writes :  "  Our  faculties  carry  us 
no  further  toward  the  knowledge  and  distinction  of  substances,  than 
a  collection  of  those  sensible  ideas  which  we  observe  in  them.  .  .  . 
A  blind  man  may  as  soon  sort  things  by  their  color,  and  he  that 
has  lost*  his  smell  as  well  distinguish  a  lily  and  a  rose  by  their 
odor,  as  by  those  internal  constitutions  which  he  knows  not."  6 
Locke  returns  to  this  contention  with  a  wearisome  prolixity,  but 
is  rarely  at  variance  with  the  conclusion,  that  we  never  know  an 
object's  real  essence,  but  its  nominal  essence  only;  and  constantly 
questions  the  legitimacy  even  to  assume  the  existence  of  a  real 
essence, — "  that  inherent  constitution  which  everything  has  within 
itself,  without  any  relation  to  anything  without  it."7 

From  the  standpoint  of  his  radical  relativity,8  the  same  negative 
conclusion  is  reached,  with  this  differenece  only,  that,  in  accord 
with  the  former  viewpoint,  their  unknowable  character  is  what  gets 
emphasized,  whereas,  in  the  latter  case,  it  is  their  non-existence  that 
is  emphasized. 

Thus  reduced  to  our  simple  ideas,  we  may  ask  whether  they 
have  any  natural  and  visible  "connections  and  dependencies," 
whereby  guidance  is  yielded  in  the  proper  formation  of  our  par- 
ticular complex  ideas?  And  here  Locke's  answer,  in  general 
theory,  is  again  consistently  negative.9  Hence  Locke's  conclusion, 
that  our  complex  ideas,  of  which  there  are,  according  to  him,  three 
distinct  sorts, — modes,  substances,  and  relations, — "  are  of  man's, 
and  not  of  nature's  making."  In  regard  to  mixed  modes,  his  gen- 
eral contention  is,  "that  they  are  not  only  made  by  the  mind,  but 
made  very  arbitrarily,  made  without  patterns  or  reference  to  any 
real  existence.  Wherein  they  differ  from  those  of  substances, 
which  carry  with  them  the  suggestion  of  some  real  being,  from 
which  they  are  taken,  and  to  which  they  are  conformable."10 

I  have  now  sufficiently  outlined,  in  general  theory,  the  second 
step  in  Locke's  philosophy.  But  this  second  step,  so  easily  over- 
looked as  a  second  step,  and  so  commonly  regarded  as  a  subordinate 
phase  only  of  the  first  step  in  his  argument,  instead  of  the  reverse, 
calls  for  a  few  additional  considerations  at  this  point. 

The  problem  which  particularly  concerns  Locke  after  he  has 
once  settled  the  claim  that  it  is  the  nominal  and  not  the  real  essence 

6.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sec.  9. 

7.  Ibid.,  sec.  6. 

8.  This  term  will  receive  explanation  in  the  next  chapter. 

9.  See  Bk.  IV,  ch.  3,  sees.  28-29. 

10.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  5,  sec.  3. 


14 

"  which  determines  the  sorts  of  things,"  may  be  made  to  take  the 
following  form :  what  constitutes  the  "  measure  and  boundary  "  of 
each  particular  thing,  whereby  it  is  made  that  particular  thing,  and 
distinguished  from  others?  And  his  answer  is :  an  object's  measure 
and  boundary  is  the  "  workmanship  of  the  mind,"  operative  within 
the  nominal  essence,  and  a  matter  of  definition  or  abstract  idea; 
that  is,  a  construct.  This  answer,  as  elaborated  in  Locke,  suffers 
in  cogency,  only  where  he  persists  in  his  exaggerated  theoretical 
claim,  that  "  there  is  no  individual  parcel  of  matter  to  which  any 
of  its  qualities  are  so  annexed  as  to  be  essential  to  it  or  inseparable 
from  it,"11  and  rendered  with  the  meaning,  that  every  particular 
parcel  of  matter  reduces  to  pure  flux,  as  it  were ;  reduces  to  a  degree 
of  variability  or  instability  never  experienced  save  in  a  theory 
which  ignores  varying  degrees  of  instability  and  varying  degrees 
of  stability,  as  commonly  experienced.  It  is  only  when  thus 
rendered  that  it  is  necessary  for  him  to  find  the  sole  principle  of 
stability  of  permanence  in  a  realm  other  than  that  of  matter-of- 
fact.  But  it  is  in  this  version  only  that  his  notion  of  the  definition 
or  abstract  idea  as  constituting  the  "  essence  "  of  a  thing,  namely, 
its  measure  and  boundary,  chimes  in  with  his  generally  assumed 
dualism,  or  absolute  divorce,  between  "  fact "  and  "  meaning  ",  in 
the  varied  forms  this  divorce  assumes  in  his  Essay.  Thus  formu- 
lated, Locke's  doctrine  were  indeed  a  doctrine  of  (a  rationalistic 
type  of)  relativity  of  a  most  extreme  and  exaggerated  sort;  but  it 
would  be  a  type  of  relativity  where  everything  was  attributed  to  the 
function  of  thought,  only  to  be  dashed  to  naught  by  one  fell  stroke : 
"  nothing  exists  but  particulars  " ; — which,  doctrine,  when  pushed  to 
extremes,  and  as  Locke's  writings  only  too  frequently  favor,  practi- 
cally means,  that  all  knowledge  is  irrelevant.  "  Nothing  exists  but 
particulars  !"  But  if  "  particulars  "  as  indicated,  are  so  elastic  in 
content  as  to  imply  any  content  from  a  mere  blank  to  the  universe, 
how  again  avoid  an  interminable  see-saw?  Above  the  level  of  a 
mere  zero,  the  "  particular "  would  thus  again  openly  negate 
knowledge  only  itself  tacitly  to  usurp  it. 

In  holding,  then,  as  Locke  does,  that  "  each  distinct  idea  is  a 
distinct  essence,"  nothing  more  is  implied  than  that  sucn  deteF" 
mination  or  boundary  of  a  thing,  as  of  this  or  that  kmr),  is  given  in 
an  abstract  idea  or  definition,  which,  although  in  one  sense  less 
complete  than  reality,  in  another  sense,  exceeds  it.  It  is  incom- 
plete or  inadequate  in  respect  to  the  sum  total  of  its  potential  quali- 

11.  Ibid.,  ch.  6,  sec.  6. 


15 

ties;  but  in  respect  to  its  momentary  existences,  all  alike  partial 
and'  variable,  it  is  in  excess  oi:  any  sill'li  single  iiiHJun'ce  of  its  actual 
existence.  For,  at  any  moment,  any  given  object  may  possess 
almost  any  quality  and  los'e  almost  any  ot  its  qualities  the  next. 
'There  is  a  need  ot  unity  in  the  midst  of  diversity;  nence"Tns" 
conception  of  an  object  as  a  construct, — involving  a  description 
ot  an  object  in  -Locke  truly  marvelous,  not 'only  because  it  emerges 
out  ot  a  sea  oi:  comracttctions  and  prepossessions,  but,  because  in 
the  form  it  finally  assumes,  it  stands  unsurpassed^  The  question 
is  not  whether  we  have  gotten  beyond  .Locke;  rather  is  it  the 
question  whether  we  have  caught  up  to  him.  Back  to  Book  III  is 
the  plea  urged  upon  us  for  a  proper  understanding  of  the  other 
Books. 


CHAPTER  II 

RELATIVITY  DEFINED  AND  LOCKERS  POSITION  INDICATED  IN  RKSPKC'T 
TO    ITS   VARIOUS    FORMULATIONS 

STATED  in  its  most  general  form,  the  principle  of  relativity 
properly  denotes  the  theory  that  every  object  determines  and  is 
determined  by  every  other  object;1  and,  as  commonly  considered, 
supports  the  claims  that  no  object,  at  any  point  of  its  history,  is 
incapable  of  a  further  reduction  or  decomposition;  nor,  at  any 
point  in  its  further  growth  or  complexity,  incapable  of  a  still  higher 
synthesis  or  composition.  Conceived  in  this  form,  I  designate  the 
principle  radical  relativity.  This  formulation  of  it  is  the  one  that 
is  most  commonly  encountered,  and  it  has  its  usual  and  explicit 
statement  in  Locke.  His  more  peculiar  and  frequent  expression  of 
it,  however,  is  the  following:  "Substances  when  truly  considered 
are  powers,  and  hence  nothing  else  than  so  many  relations  to  other 
substances."2 

Radical  relativity  is  no  doubt  sound  enough  in  abstract  theory. 
Its  emphasis  is  upon  mutual  dependence  among  objects, — the 
postulate  of  all  scientific  inquiry.  But  to  talk  of  an  object's  depen- 
dence in  general  and  to  talk  of  a  particular  object's  dependence 
upon  other  particular  objects  in  a  given  situation,  is  a  very  dilVercnt 
thing.  When  discoursing  upon  this  matter  of  mutual  depend  (Mice 
in  the  abstract,  the  dependence  of  objects  admits  of  no  partiality: 
they  are  all  thought  equally  dependent  and  they  are  all  thought 
completely  dependent;  their  independence,  if  thought  to  have  any, 
vanishing  like  mist  in  the  morning  air,  the  more  its  central  tenet 
of  mutual  dependence  gets  its  emphasis.  Such  is  the  criticism 
commonly  directed  against  relativity  of  the  so-called  radical  type. 
To  what  extent  is  it  valid? 

To  insist  upon  a  complete  dependence  among  objects  is  valid. 
It  is  the  postulate  of  all  scientific  inquiry  and  expresses  our  faith 

1.  See  Baldwin's  Dictionary;    Article  on  Belativity. 

2.  Bk.  II,  ch.  24,  sec.  37. 

1(5 


17 

in  an  object's  inherent  rationality.  But  objects  are  not  equally 
dependent  upon  each  other  in  any  given  situation;  they  do  not  in 
general,  in  specific  situations,  entail  a  perfect  equivalence  of  give- 
and-take;  and  as  knowledge  begins  with  the  given,  it  is  equally 
reflective  of  the  scientific  spirit  to  hold  strictly  to  the  facts  as  thus 
revealed.  The  dependence  of  a  given  object  in  a  given  situation 
may  be  large,  yet  the  dependence  of  the  other  objects  upon  it  or 
upon  each  other  in  that  particular  situation  may  be  a  zero.  The 
unaffected  objects  are  accordingly  more  properly  designated  as 
independent.  But  an  independence  properly  maintained  for  an 
object  in  certain  situations  may  in  other  situations  convert  itself 
into  a  dependence,  as  our  scientific  postulate  of  mutual  dependence 
would  naturally  dispose  us  to  expect.  In  so  far  then,  as  we  remain 
strictly  empirical,  and,  further,  strictly  adhere  to  our  confessed 
postulate,  the  following  form  of  relativity  seems  the  more  permis- 
sible one :  objects  reveal  themselves  differently  in  different  situa- 
tions, and  in  different  situations  capable  of  revealing  qualities 
often  absolutely  incompatible  with  each  other.  Eelativity  thus 
conceived,  I  term  empirical.  Locke's  common  expression  of  it 
takes  on  the  following  form :  "  The  changes  which  one  '  body ' 
is  apt  to  receive  from  or  produce  in  other  '  bodies/  upon  a  due 
application,  exceeds  far,  not  only  what  we  know,  but  what  we  are 
apt  to  imagine."  3 

These  considerations  conduct  us  to  the  third  form  which  I  am 
inclined  to  affirm  the  principle  in  question  assumes.  I  term  it 
constructive  relativity.  Let  me  explain.  If  objects  reveal  them- 
selves differently  in  different  situations  and  in  different  situations 
capable  of  revealing  qualities  often  absolutely  incompatible  with 
each  other,  then  the  conclusion  follows,  as  in  opposition  to  the  con- 
clusion reached  by  radical  relativity,  that  no  single  situation  of 
actual  existence  can  reveal  or  exhaust  an  object's  total  actuality, 
all  its  possible  phases  or  qualities.  It  is  in  its  very  nature  a  multi- 
plicity, viewed  spatially  or  temporally.  Such  unity  as  may  be 
ascribed  to  it,  Locke  assigns  to  the  function  of  the  so-called  abstract 
idea,  and  the  object  that  results  accordingly  viewed  in  the  light  of 

3.  Ibid.,  ch.  31,  sec.  10.  By  insisting  upon  the  distinction  between  the 
abstract  and  the  empirical  basis  of  the  relativistic  principle,  I  feel  I  fully 
meet  the  objection  commonly  directed  against  it;  namely,  that  objects, 
according  to  it,  resolve  themselves  into  a  sheer  network  of  empty  relations. 
In  addition  to  what  has  already  been  stated,  it  need  only  be  said  that  rela- 
tions, or,  to  be  more  specific,  pariculars,  are  as  effective  in  reinforcing  each 
other  and  preserving  each  other  intact,  as  they  are  in  building  each  other  up 
or  in  destroying  each  other.  Relative  independence  is  no  less  truly  descrip- 
tive of  the  varied  situations  suggesting  it  than  dependence. 


18 

a  construct  and  not  a  copy,  "  of  man's  and  not  of  nature's  making/' 
as  we,  in  due  place,  shall  find  him  propounding  with  great  vigor. 
He  writes  in  general  to  the  following  effect :  "  It  is  not  unity  of 
substances  that  comprehends  all  sorts  of  identity,  or  will  determine 
it  in  every  case ;  but  to  conceive  and  judge  of  it  aright  .  .  .  what- 
ever does  or  can  exist,  or  be  considered  as  one  thing  is  positive,  and 
so  not  only  simple  ideas  and  substances,  but  modes  also  are  positive 
beings:  though  the  parts  of  which  they  consist  are  often  relative 
one  to  another  ...  it  sufficing  to  the  unity  of  every  idea  that  it 
be  considered  as  one  representation  or  picture,  though  made  up  of 
ever  so  many  particulars."  4  The  statement  involves  the  contention 
already  enunciated  that  things,  however,  partial  or  variable  in  their 
matter-of-fact  existence  of  this  or  that  moment,  are  determined 
in  their  character  of  this  or  that  sort  or  whole  by  the  idea ;  namely, 
that  "  men  determine  sorts,"5  specific  things,  which,  in  accord  with 
his  declared  relativit}T,  he  denies  as  existing  "  in  nature  with  .any 
prefixed  bounds."6 

For  the  sake  of  completeness,  I  mention  two  additional  forms 
of  the  relativistic  principle  to  which  historic  thought  has  given 
specific  formulation  and  currency,  and  with  which  certain  phases  of 
his  doctrine  may  be  further  identified. 

Protagoras  is  made  the  exponent  of  one  of  these  specific  formu- 
lations ;  the  doctrine  that  "  all  knowledge  is  merely  phenomenal," 
expresses  another  specific  formulation.  The  former  is  based,  in  the 
main,  upon  a  recognized  and  broadly  affirmed  diversity  in  our  per- 
ceptions of  a  given  object;  the  latter,  upon  the  claim  that  an  object 
(to  quote  Mill)  "is  known  to  us  only  in  one  special  relation; 
namely,  as  that  which  produces,  or  is  capable  of  producing,  certain 
impressions  on  our  senses;  and  all  that  we  really  know  is  these 
impressions.  This  is  the  doctrine  of  the  Relativity  of  Knowledge 
to  the  knowing  mind,  in  the  simplest,  purest,  and,  as  I  think,  the- 
most  proper  acceptation  of  the  word."  (See  Thomson's  Diction- 
ary; Art.,  Relativity.)  The  Protagorean  type  of  relativity,  as  we 
shall  perceive  further  along  in  our  stud}%  is  fundamental  to  Locke's 
elaboration  of  so-called  constructive  relativity. 

To  complete  this  survey,7  another  specific  formulation  of  Rela- 
tivity requires  mentioning.  Spencer  gives  the  following  graphic 
description  of  it:  "Every  thought/'  he  says,  "involves  a  whole 

4.  Ibid.,  ch.  25,  sec.  6;  ch.  24,  sec.  1. 

5.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sec.  35. 

6.  Ibid.,  sec.  29. 

7.  I  do  not  mention  Relativity  as  recognized  and  formulated  in  Physics 
and  Psychology. 


19 

system  of  thoughts;  and  ceases  to  exist  if  severed  from  its  various 
correlatives.  As  we  cannot  isolate  a  single  organ  of  a  living  body, 
and  deal  with  it  as  if  it  had  a  life  independent  of  the  rest ;  so,  from 
the  organized  structure  of  our  cognitions,  we  cannot  cut  one  out  and 
proceed  as  though  it  had  survived  the  separation.  ...  A  developed 
intelligence  can  arise  only  by  a  process  which,  in  making  thoughts 
defined,  also  makes  them  mutually  dependent — establishes  among 
them  certain  vital  connections,  the  destruction  of  which  causes 
instant  death  of  the  thoughts."  (First  Prin.  sec.  39.)  8 

In  this  quotation  from  Spencer,  we  have  the  voice  of  the 
rationalist;  in  Mill's  quotation  there  appears  the  more  dominant 
note  of  the  empiricist;  both  of  which,  taken  in  conjunction  with 
the  Protagorean  type  of  Eelativity,  agree  in  one  result;  namely, 
that,  knowing  things  as  we  know  them,  is  not  knowing  them  as 
they  actually  are ;  that  the  Ding  an  sich  eternally  eludes,  even  while 
it  eternally  attracts,  us.  Hence  the  reaction  to  these  formulations 
of  knowledge  as  expressed  by  M'Cosh,  in  his  "  Intuitions  of  the 
Mind."9  "It  should  be  admitted,"  he  says,  "  (1)  that  man  knows 
only  so  far  as  he  has  the  faculties  of  knowledge;  (2)  that  he 
knows  objects  only  under  aspects  presented  to  his  faculties ;  and  (3) 
that  his  faculties  are  limited,  and  consequently  his  knowledge 
limited,  so  that,  not  only  does  he  not  know  all  objects,  but  he 
does  not  know  all  about  any  one  object.  It  may  further  be  allowed 
(4)  that  in  perception  by  the  senses  we  know  external  objects  in 
relation  to  the  perceiving  mind.  But  while  these  views  can  be 
established  in  opposition  to  the  philosophy  of  the  Absolute,  it 
should  ever  be  resolutely  maintained,  on  the  other  hand,  (1)  that 
we  know  the  very  thing;  and  (2)  that  our  knowledge  is  correct  as 
far  as  it  goes  "  (p.  344).  Here  we  have  the  iteration  of  the  realist, 
who  refuses  to  be  "  cribbed,  cabined,  and  confined  "  by  the  dogmas 
of  the  categories  and  of  sense-perception  into  which  modern 
thought  has  crystallized.  Not  very  unlike  Dr.  Johnson's  declaration 
in  respect  to  Berkeley,  a  passage  to  "  the  very  thing  itself "  is 
affirmed,  let  logic  or  dogma  proclaim  their  loudest. 

This  apart,  however,  the  sole  question  that  concerns  us  is :  How 
does  Locke  resolve  the  difficulty — Locke,  the  credited  source  of  all 
our  modern  epistemological  ills  ? 

Xo  proper  answer  to  this  question  is  possible  here.  I  venture 
the  suggestion,  however,  that  Locke  remains  consistently  relativistic 

8.  The  types  of  relativity  formulated  by  Mill  and  Spencer  in  the  above 
passages  have  no  further  bearing  upon  the  present  inquiry. 

9.  See  Thomson's  Dictionary;    Art.,  Relativity. 


20 

in  his  solution.  He  finds  that  reality,,  in  the  last  analysis,  is  deter- 
mined in  ideas,  formed  under  the  control  of  ends  or  purposes, 
within  a  world  of  relatively  determined  needs  ("beyond  which  we 
have  no  concernment  either  to  know  or  be,")  and  of  relatively 
"  unalterable  organs/'  and  where  certain  fixed,  regular,  and  con- 
stant co-existences  among  ideas  are  accepted  by  him  as  a  fact.  This 
is  at  once  relativistic,  possivistic,  pragmatic  and  constructive. 


II 

RELATIVISTIC  MOTIVES  IN  LOCKE 

CHAPTER  III 

THE  SIMPLE  IDEAS:    WHAT  AKK  THEY? 

SIMPLE  ideas  play  a  somewhat  variable  role  in  Locke's  philos- 
ophy and  the  purpose  of  this  chapter  is  to  trace  it,  and  to  define 
them  as  nearly  as  possible. 

"  One  thing/'  says  Locke,  "  is  carefully  to  be  observed  concern- 
ing the  ideas  we  have;  and  that  is,  that  some  of  them  are  simple 
and  some  complex."1  They  distinguish  themselves  in  the  fact  that 
complex  ideas  consist  in  the  unity  or  supposed  unity  of  distin- 
guishable parts,  whereas  simple  ideas,  "  being  each  in  itself  uncom- 
pounded,  contains  in  it  nothing  but  one  uniform  appearance  or 
conception  in  the  mind,  and  is  not  distinguishable  into  different 
ideas."  2  By  this  criterion,  simple  ideas  are  (a)  uncompounded,  (b) 
contain  but  one  uniform  appearance,  and  (c)  are  but  one  concep- 
tion in  the  mind.  We  shall  presently  get  to  see  that  Locke  regards 
them  as  products;  hence  compounded.  I  turn  to  the  remaining 
differentia  indicated. 

They  constitute  but  one  uniform  appearance.  Let  us  consider 
this  mark. 

Their  uniform  appearance  is  one  that  is  relative :  "  blood  that 
is  red  to  the  naked  eye  is  not  so  under  the  microscope."  3  Further, 
the  simple  modes  are  admitted  to  have  a  uniformity  or  likeness  in 
their  parts,  although  declared  to  be  complex :  space  and  time  "  are 
justly  reckoned  among  our  simple  ideas,  yet  none  of  the  distinct 
ideas  we  have  of  either  is  without  composition ;  it  is  the  very  nature 

1.  Bk.  II,  ch.  2,  sec.  1. 

2.  Ibid. 

3.  Ibid.,  ch.  23,  sees.  11-12. 

21 


22 

of  both  of  them  to  consist  of  parts ;  but  their  parts  being  all  of  the 
same  kind  .  .  .  hinder  them  not  from  having  a  place  amongst 
simple  ideas."  4  In  the  one  case  we  find  "  the  one  uniform  appear- 
ance "  a  conditioned  affair ;  in  the  latter  case,  they  are  seen  to 
share  this  "  uniform  appearance  "  in  common  with  simple  modes. 
Hence,  no  differentia. 

The  third  mark,  that  of  "  one  conception  "  in  the  mind,  also 
fails  to  be  a  differentia,  as  simple  ideas  are  herein  found  undis- 
tinguished from  complex  ideas  as  a  whole.  There  is  no  need  to 
quote  him  at  length.  The  discrepancy  from  this  standpoint  is  writ 
too  large  in  any  part  of  the  treatise  to  which  we  may  turn.  One 
citation  therefore  will  be  made  to  suffice.  "  Besides  these  complex 
ideas  of  several  single  substances,  as  of  man,  horse,  gold,  violet, 
apple,  etc.,  the  mind  hath  also  complex  collective  ideas  of  sub- 
stances; which  I  so  call,  because  such  ideas  are  made  up  of  many 
particular  substances  considered  together,  as  united  into  one  idea, 
and  which,  so  joined,  are  looked  on  as  one;  v.g.,  the  idea  of  such  a 
collection  of  men  as  made  an  army  ...  is  as  much  one  idea  as 
the  idea  of  a  man :  and  the  great  collective  idea  of  bodies  whatever, 
signified  by  the  name  world,  is  as  much  one  idea  as  the  idea  of  any 
the  least  particle  of  matter  in  it;  it  sufficing  to  the  unity  of  any 
idea,  that  it  be  considered  as  one  representation  or  picture,  though 
made  up  of  ever  so  many  particulars."  5  That  is,  between  an 
imaginary  point  and  the  universe,  unity  may  be  appropriated  by 
anything ;  either  by  the  complex  simple  idea  or  by  the  simple  com- 
plex one. 

He  next  distinguishes  between  them  in  the  fact,  that  in  the 
origin  of  simple  ideas  the  mind  is  passive,  and  that  "  it  cannot 
invent  or  frame  one  new  simple  idea  "  nor  refuse  to  have,  alter  or 
blot  out  one  of  them  when  offered  to  the  mind ;  whereas  in  the  case 
of  complex  ideas  the  mind  has  the  power  to  repeat,  compare,  and 
unite  them  to  an  infinite  variety.6  From  this  follows  his  conclu- 
sion "  that  simple  ideas  are  the  material  of  all  our  knowledge,"  7 
and  that  we  have  "  no  complex  idea  not  made  out  of  those  simple 
ones."  A  total  dependence  upon  reality  for  our  simple  ideas,  and 
a  complete  independence  of  reality  in  regard  to  complex  ideas,  is 
the  distinction  which  discloses  itself  here.  The  mind,  in  its  com- 
plex ideas,  would  appear  totally  dependent  upon  the  simple  ideas, 

4.  Ibid.,  ch.   15,  sec.  9. 

5.  Ibid.,  ch.  24,  sec.  1. 

6.  Ibid.,  ch.  2,  sec.  2. 

7.  Ibid.,  ch.  7,  sec.  4. 


23 

but,  other  than  that,  the  impression  conveyed  is  that  complex  ideas 
neither  require  nor  disclose  any  further  dependence  upon  a  reality 
and  general  constitution  of  things.  And  yet  Locke's  distinction 
between  complex  ideas  of  modes  and  substances  is  grounded  just 
in  this  particular  fact,  that  modes,  within  simple  ideas,  are  more  or 
less  purely  of  the  mind's  invention,  whereas  substances  are  declared 
to  be  dependent,  not  only  upon  the  simple  ideas,  but  upon  "the 
supposition  of  some  real  being,  from  which  they  are  taken,  and  to 
which  they  are  conformable."  8  The  affirmed  distinction  then  be- 
tween complex  ideas  and  simple  ideas  cannot  be  based  upon  the 
fact  that,  in  the  origin  of  simple  ideas,  the  mind  is  wholly  depend- 
ent and  passive,  and  the  opposite  in  respect  to  complex  ideas;  for, 
as  indicated,  substances  are  dependent  beyond  simple  ideas  in  a 
wray  that  modes  are  not.  As  to  Locke's  motive  in  thus  ascribing 
a  dependence  of  the  mind  upon  reality,  the  copy-view  theory  asserts 
itself,  wherein  he  affirms,  that,  in  the  case  of  simple  ideas,  as  is 
evident,  the  mind,  not  unlike  "  a  mirror,  cannot  refuse,  alter,  or 
obliterate  the  images  or  ideas  which  the  objects  before  it  do  therein 
produce."9  This  copy- view  of  his,  however,  even  when  thus 
falsely  restricted  within  his  theory  to  simple  ideas,  gets  to  encounter 
several  set-backs  in  his  pages.  The  first  is  that  our  senses  may  not 
be  proportionate  to  or  commensurate  with  the  demands,  variety, 
and  richness  of  reality.  To  this  effect,  I  quote  the  following :  "  I 
think  it  is  not  possible  for  any  one  to  imagine  any  other  qualities 
in  bodies,  however  constituted,  whereby  they  can  be  taken  notice  of, 
besides  sounds,  taste,  smells,  visible  and  tangible  qualities.  .  .  . 
But  how  much  these  few  and  narrow  inlets  are  disproportionate  to 
the  vast  whole  extent  of  all  beings  will  not  be  hard  to  persuade 
those  who  are  not  so  foolish  as  to  think  their  span  the  measure  of 
all  things.  What  other  simple  ideas  it  is  possible  the  creatures  in 
other  parts  of  the  universe  may  have,  by  the  assistance  of  senses 
and  faculties  more  (in  number)  or  more  perfect  than  we  have,  or 
different  from  ours,  it  is  not  for  us  to  determine  .  .  .  and  a  great 
presumption  to  deny." 10 

The  second  set-back  is  experienced  where  he  gets  to  distinguish 
between  primary  qualities  as  alone  copies  and  secondary  qualities 
as  effects.  "  There  is  nothing  like  our  ideas  existing  in  the  bodies 
themselves  .  .  .  and  what  is  sweet,  blue  or  warm  in  idea,  is  but  the 
certain  bulk,  figure  and  motion  of  the  insensible  parts  in  the 

8.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  5,  sec.  3. 

9.  Bk.  II,  ch.  1,  sec.  25. 

10.  Ibid.,  ch.  2,  sec.  3,  and  Bk.  IV,  ch.  3,  sec.  22. 


24 

bodies  themselves." X1  Hence  he  regards  it  as  possible  to  have 
"  positive  ideas  even  from  privative  causes."  12  Thus  the  ideas  of 
"heat  and  cold,  light  and  darkness,  white  and  black,  motion  and 
rest  are  equally  clear  and  positive  ideas  in  the  mind ;  though,  per- 
haps, some  of  the  causes  which  produce  them  are  barely  privations 
in  the  subjects  (objects)  from  whence  our  senses  derive  these 
ideas."  13 

The  original  position  gets  itself  still  further  complicated  when 
the  simple  ideas,  viewed  as  effects,  are  found  to  be  conditioned  by 
the  particular  character  and  structure  of  the  sense-organs,  no  less 
so  and  to  no  less  extent,  than  as  conditioned  by  the  structure  of 
the  "  insensible  parts  "  of  an  object.  "  Had  we  senses  acute  enough 
to  discern  the  minute  particles  of  bodies,  and  the  real  constitution 
in  which  their  sensible  qualities  depend,  I  doubt  not  but  they  would 
produce  quite  different  ideas  in  us :  and  that  which  is  now  the  yel- 
low color  of  gold  would  then  disappear,  and  instead  of  it  we 
should  see  an  admirable  texture  of  parts.  .  .  .  This  microscopes 
plainly  discover  to  us;  for  what  to  our  naked  eyes  produce  a  cer- 
tain color,  is,  by  augmenting  the  acuteness  of  our  senses,  discov- 
ered to  be  quite  a  different  thing."  14  Thus  simple  ideas,  instead 
of  being  simple,  underived,  unconditioned,  are  found  complex, 
derived  and  conditioned;  and,  instead  of  being  copies  of  objects, 
are  effects ;  and,  instead  of  effects  produced  solely  by  the  "  insensi- 
ble part"  of  bodies,  they  are  effects  equally  conditioned  in  their 
character  by  the  particular  character  and  structure  of  the  sensible 
organism ;  and,  in  the  case  of  positive  ideas  resulting  from  privative 
causes,  almost  exclusively  conditioned,  according  to  Locke's  state- 
ments, by  the  sensible  organism.  Here,  then,  we  have  the  prin- 
ciple of  relativity  wholly  installed  within  the  sacred  precincts  of 
even  the  simple  ideas.  In  these  changes  registered  in  Locke's  view 
of  them,  they  become  increasingly  regarded  as  working  assump- 
tions, and  less  and  less  as  established  facts;  and,  as  is  equally 
apparent,  the  need  of  psychology  grows  less  relevant  to  his  argu- 
ments. Simple  ideas  thus  get  more  and  more  to  fill  the  place  of 
the  necessary  '  term }  in  the  term-relation  motive,  to  be  indicated  in 
subsequent  chapters,  as  well  as  the  ( part '  in  the  part- whole  rela- 
tion. They  preserve  a  uniqueness,  but  it  is  a  uniqueness  in  kind, 


11.  Ibid.,  ch.  8,  sec.  15. 

12.  Ibid.,  sec.  1-6. 

13.  Ibid.,  sec.  2. 

14.  Ibid.,  ch.  23,  seci.  11-12. 


25 

and  not  one  of  simplicity  or  unity.  The  simple  modes,  as  we  per- 
ceived, are  no  less  simple  ideas  of  a  kind;  just  as  pleasure  and 
pain,  succession,  change,  co-existence,  etc.,  are  others  as  ultimate 
and  as  unique  in  their  kind.  Future  chapters  will  show  how  con- 
sistently this  motive  works  out  in  his  pages. 


CHAPTER  IV 

THE    PART-WHOLE    MOTIVE 

THE  part-whole  motive,  as  it  unrolls  itself  in  connection  with 
mixed  modes  and  substances,  concerns  itself  with  the  question, 
<(  how  such  a  precise  multitude  of  parts  "  as  manifested  in  such 
complex  ideas,  "  come  to  make  but  one  idea."  His  solution  of  the 
matter  I  have  reserved  for  a  later  chapter.  Here  I  intend  to  con- 
sider the  simple  modes  as  a  phase  of  this  same  motive.  How  do 
Space,  Time,  Number,  Infinity,  Power  come  to  be?  They  are 
not  simple,  and  yet  he  holds  "  that  they  are  justly  reckoned  amongst 
our  simple  ideas/'  *  Wherein  then  lie  their  complexity ;  wherein 
their  simplicity?  It  is  sufficient  for  our  purpose  here  to  con- 
sider the  modes  of  Space  and  Time  only.  They  are  complex  be- 
cause "they  consist  of  parts,  even  though  their  parts  are  not  sep- 
arable one  from  another."  2  Their  parts  are  such  as  in  each  case 
naturally  to  involve  and  presuppose  each  other. 

But  just  whereof  do  the  parts  consist?  His  answer  is  this: 
"  Could  the  mind,  as  in  Number,  come  to  so  small  a  part  of  exten- 
sion or  duration  as  excluded  divisibility,  that  would  be,  as  it  were, 
the  indivisible  unit  or  idea,  by  repetition  of  which  it  would  make 
its  more  enlarged  ideas  of  extension  and  duration.  But  since  the 
mind  is  not  able  to  frame  an  idea  of  any  space  without  parts, 
instead  thereof  it  makes  use  of  the  common  measures  which,  by 
familiar  use,  in  each  country,  have  imprinted  themselves  in  the 
in  the  memory  (as  inches  and  feet;  seconds,  minutes,  hours,  days, 
years.)  .  .  .  Every  part  of  duration  is  duration  too,  and  every  part 
of  extension  is  extension,  both  of  them  capable  of  addition  or  divi- 
sion in  infinitum.  But  the  least  portions  of  either  of  them  whereof 
we  have  clear  and  distinct  ideas  may  perhaps  be  fittest  to  be  con- 
sidered by  us  as  the  simple  ideas  of  that  kind  out  of  which  our 
complex  modes  of  space,  extension  and  duration  are  made  up,  and 
into  which  they  can  again  be  distinctly  resolved."  :  "We  have  no 
absolute  unit  of  space  and  no  absolute  unit  of  time;  hence  "no 

1.  Bk.  II,  ch.  15,  sec.  9;  eh.  21,  sec.  3. 

2.  Ibid.,  ch.  15,  sec.  10. 

3.  Ibid.,  sec.  9.    Italics  mine. 

26 


27 

two  parts  of  duration  can  be  certainly  known  to  be  equal."  4  We 
try  to  control  the  situation,  lacking  such  absolute  units,  by  prac- 
tical devices  of  one  kind  or  another,  involving  regular,  periodic 
motions,  "of  which  seeming  equality,  however,  we  have  no  other 
measure,  but  such  as  the  train  of  our  ideas  lodged  in  our  memories, 
with  the  concurrence  of  other  probable  reasons,  to  persuade  us 
of  their  equality."  5  In  a  word,  our  notions  of  time  and  space 
are  sheer  constructs,  and  in  their  abstract  character,  capable  in  one 
direction  of  an  infinite  expansion,  and  in  the  other  direction,  of  an 
infinite  divisibility. 

But  in  this  absence  of  an  absolute  unit  of  space  or  time,  what 
gives  occasion  for  their  formation?  The  facts  of  change,  motion, 
and  succession,  and  that  of  distance  and  place,  as  well  as  existing 
needs  for  unity  or  order.  Of  change,  Locke  writes:  "Wherever 
change  is  observed,  the  mind  must  collect  a  power  somewhere  able 
to  make  that  change,  as  well  as  a  possibility  in  the  thing  itself  to 
receive  it " ; 6  and  he  might  have  said  the  same  of  succession,  which 
he  holds  conditions  our  notion  of  time:  wherever  succession  is 
observed,  the  mind  must  collect  a  notion  somewhere  able  to  make 
the  fact  of  succession  a  possibility. 

But  such  facts  as  change,  etc.,  it  may  be  held,  are  both  complex 
and  relative.  True,  and  Locke  not  only  admits  as  much  but  puts 
himself  at  pains  to  prove  this  very  contention.  But  he  was  shown 
to  prove  as  much  concerning  the  simple  ideas  in  general.  What 
then  becomes  of  our  so-termed  parts,  whether  a  color  or  sound,  or 
the  facts  of  succession  and  change?  We  accept  the  ideas  of  color 
and  sound  as  ultimate;  then  succession,  change,  motion,  place,  dis- 
tance, involving  aspects  equally  as  unique  and  irreducible,  are 
equally  as  ultimate.  And  what  is  more,  in  respect  to  succession, 
he  institutes  a  difference  between  a  perceived  and  a  conceived  suc- 
cession ;  "  it  seems  to  me  that  the  constant  and  regular  succession 
of  ideas  in  a  waking  man,  is,  as  it  were,  the  measure  and'  standard 
of  all  other  succession :  whereof,  if  any  one  either  exceeds  the  pace 
of  our  ideas,  as  where  two  sounds  or  pains,  etc.,  take  up  in  their  suc- 
cession the  duration  of  but  one  idea,  or  else  where  any  motion  or 
succession  is  so  slow,  as  that  it  keeps  not  pace  with  the  idea  in  our 
minds,  or  the  quickness  in  which  they  take  their  turns  .  .  . 
there  also  the  sense  of  a  constant  continued  succession  is  lost,  and 

4.  Ibid.,  sec.  21. 

').  Tbid. 

G.   ILirl.,  ch.  21,  sec.  4. 


28 

we  perceive  it  not/' 7  In  either  event,  he  goes  on  to  say,  "  we  must 
have  recourse  to  other  means  for  determining  the  fact  of  a  suc- 
cession "  as  existing  in  this  or  that  object,  "  which  we  then  per- 
ceive by  the  change  of  distance  that  it  hath  moved,  yet  the  motion 
itself  we  perceive  not."  8 

The  formation  of  the  simple  modes  then  are  conditioned  by  cer- 
tain ultimate  distinguishable  phases  of  reality,  "  and  are  made  use 
of  to  denote  the  position  of  finite  real  beings,  in  respect  one  to 
another,  in  those  uniform  infinite  oceans  of  duration  and 
space.  .  .  .  From  such  points  fixed  in  sensible  beings  we  reckon, 
and  from  them  we  measure  our  portions  of  those  infinite  quantities ; 
which,  so  considered,  are  that  which  we  call  time  and  place.  For 
duration  and  space  being  in  themselves  uniform  and  boundless,  the 
order  and  position  of  things,  without  such  known  settled  points, 
would  be  lost  in  them;  and  all  tilings  would  lie  jumbled  in  an 
incurable  confusion."  9 

How  then  do  our  simple  modes  come  to  be?  This  question  I 
think  I  have  answered.  The}r  are  constructs  inevitably  involved  in 
the  comprehension  of  certain  organizable  aspects,  parts,  or  phases 
of  experience;  their  peculiar  kind  or  quality,  in  each  case,  being 
in  a  sense  dependent  upon  the  peculiar  aspect  of  the  parts  or  phases 
involved,  "  and  therefore  we  are  not  to  wonder  that  we  compre- 
hend them  not  .  .  .  when  we  would  consider  them  either  abstractly 
in  themselves"  or  in  their  ontological  character  (if  they  really  pos- 
sess such)  ;  they  work  successfully  in  preventing  an  "  incurable 
confusion";  and  hence  are  real  pragmatically;  whether  they  are 
real  ontologically,  Locke  gives  us  no  ground  for  concluding  one 
way  or  the  other.10 

7.  Ibid.,  ch.  14,  sec.  12.    Sees.  9-17.    Italics  are  mine. 

8.  Ibid.,  sec.  11.      • 

9.  Ibid.,  ch.  15,  sec.  5;    also  sees.  6-10. 

10.  His  conclusion  is  beautifully  summed  up  in  the  following  quotation: 
' '  Where  and  when  are  questions  belonging  to  all  finite  existences,  and  are  by 
us  always  reckoned  from  some  certain  epochs  marked  out  to  us  by  the  motions 
observable  in  it.  Without  some  such  fixed  parts  or  periods,  the  order  of 
things  would  be  lost  to  our  finite  understandings  in  the  boundless  variable 
oceans  of  (abstract  or  conceptual)  duration  and  expansion;  which  compre- 
hend in  them  all  finite  beings,  and  in  their  full  extent  belong  only  to  the 
Deity.  And  therefore  we  are  not  to  wonder  that  we  comprehend  them  not, 
and  do  so  often  find  our  thoughts  at  a  loss,  when  we  would  consider  them 
either  abstractly  in  themselves,  or  as  any  way  attributed  to  the  first  incom- 
prehensible Being.  But  when  applied  to  any  particular  finite  being,  the 
extension  of  any  body  is  so  much  of  that  infinite  space  as  the  bulk  of  the 
body  takes  up ;  ...  all  which  distances  we  measure  by  preconceived  ideas 
of  certain  lengths  of  space  and  duration,  as  inches,  feet,  miles;  and,  in  the 
other,  minutes,  days,  years,  etc."  Ibid.,  sec.  8. 


CHAPTER  V 

THE  TERM-RELATIOX  MOTIVE 

THE  term-relation  motive  in  Locke  swings  between  the  extreme 
views  of  ontological  particulars  and  of  a  radical  relativity.  In 
accord  to  the  latter  motive,  he  writes :  "  This  is  certain :  things 
however  absolute  and  entire  they  may  seem  in  themselves  are  but 
retainers  to  other  parts  of  nature,  for  that  which  they  are  most 
taken  notice  of  by  us;  .  .  .  and  there  is  not  so  complete  and 
perfect  a  part  that  we  know  of  nature  which  does  not  owe  the 
being  it  has,  and  the  excellencies  of  it,  to  its  neighbors ;  and  we 
must  not  confine  our  thoughts  within  the  surface  of  any  body,  but 
look  a  great  deal  further,  to  comprehend  perfectly  those  qualities 
that  are  in  it."  *  In  respect  to  the  former  view,  he  writes :  "  The 
immediate  object  of  all  our  reasoning  and  knowledge  is  nothing 
but  particulars.  .  .  .  Universality  is  but  accidental  to  it."  2  Uni- 
versality, we  read  elsewhere,  "  belongs  not  to  things  themselves, 
which  are  all  of  them  particular  in  their  existence,  even  those  words 
and  ideas  which  in  their  signification  are  general.  When  therefore 
we  quit  particulars,  the  universals  that  rest  are  only  creatures  of 
our  own  making;  their  general  nature  being  nothing  but  the 
capacity  they  are  put  into  by  the  understanding  of  signifying  or 
representing  particulars."  3  By  particulars,  Locke  seems  to  imply 
"  anything  as  existing  in  any  determined  time  and  place  ",4  and  by 
universals  he  denotes  meaning  or  any  other  thought  product. 
The  universal,  however,  is  merely  accidental  to  particulars. 
Thought  may  create  universals  and  these  in  turn  may  become  par- 
ticulars; but  they  are  particulars  which  permit  the  original  par- 
ticulars, from  which  thought  took  its  rise,  to  remain  wholly  unal- 
tered. Thought  may  have  a  function,  but  it  is  a  merely  specious, 

1.  Bk.  IV.,  ch.  6,  sec.  11. 

2.  Ibid.,  ch.   17,  sec.  8. 

3.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  3,  sec.  11. 

4.  Bk.  II,  ch.  27,  sec.  1. 

29 


30 

vapid  function,  ending,  as  with  the  radical  realist  in  general,  just 
where  it  began,  the  original  particulars  suffering  little  disturb- 
ance in  their  ontological  peace,  whether  thought  appeared  on  the 
scene  or  not.  But  suppose  we  identify  particulars  with  Locke's 
other  specified  particulars;  namely,  simple  and  complex  ideas;  and 
if  particulars  refuse  to  be  thus  assimilated,  our  only  alternative  is 
to  identify  them  with  real  essences;  and  then,  of  course,  what  is 
said  of  either,  will  hold  equally  true  of  particulars.  It  seems  to 
me  nothing  more  remains  to  be  said  on  the  subject.  Unless  thus 
capable  of  being  assimilated,  they  remain  wholly  foreign  to  and 
outside  of  his  philosophy  as  the  "  new  way  of  ideas/' 

The  ontological  particular,  however,  does  not  represent 
Locke's  only  anti-relativistic  motive.  Chapter  VII  shall  concern 
itself  with  a  very  significant  phase  of  it,  and  might  be  described  as 
the  primacy  of  the  clear  and  distinct  ideas,  as  opposed  to  and  inde- 
pendent of  meaning  and  knowledge  as  grounded  solely  in  and 
confined  solely  to  the  relations  of  such  ideas. 

When  we  come  to  Locke's  distinction  of  the  primary-secondary 
qualities,  the  particular  appears  resurrected.  The  following  is  a 
typical  passage  :  "  Our  senses  failing  us  in  the  discovery  of  the  bulk, 
texture  and  figure  of  the  minute  parts  of  bodies,  on  which  their 
real  constitutions  and  differences  depend,  we  are  fain  to  make  use 
of  their  secondary  qualities  as  the  characteristical  marks  and  notes 
whereby  to  frame  ideas  of  them  in  our  minds,  and  distinguish  them 
one  from  another :  all  which  secondary  qualities  are  nothing  but 
.  .  .  mere  powers  depending  on  its  primary  qualities."  5  Here  we 
have  two  distinct  positions  enunciated  in  respect  to  our  insensible 
objects  and  the  secondary  qualities  as  depending  upon  them.  First, 
that  primary  qualities  constitute  the  insensible  object,  and,  secondly, 
that  "  the  secondary  qualities  as  the  characteristical  marks  and 
notes  "  serve  "  to  distinguish  "  such  objects  one  from  another.  The 
"first  assertion  involves  the  contradiction  that  the  primary  qualities, 
as  but  a  division  within  simple  ideas,  and,  therefore,  sensible,  are 
also  to  be  identified  with  the  insensible  real  constitution  of  bodies. 
But  to  identify  them  with  such  real  constitution  is  to  identify  them 
with  the  unknown  and  non-existent.  The  second  assertion  involves 
the  claim  that  the  secondary  qualities  constitute  the  sole  data  of 
knowledge  and  are  effects  rather  than  products;  they  are  further  the 
"characteristical  marks  and  notes"  whereby  we  determine  ;:n<l 
distinguish  things  one  from  another.  The  latter  position 

5.  Ibid.,  ch.  23,  sec.  8. 


31 

sents  the  phenomenal  type  of  relativity.  Let  us  consider  these 
various  statements  in  detail. 

In  the  first  place,  I  seek  to  protest  that  the  data  of  knowledge 
are  confined  to  the  secondary  qualities.  In  addition  to  the  data 
specified  and  recognized  in  the  previous  chapter  as  on  a  par  with  the 
secondary  qualities  as  ultimate  and  irreducible  data,  co-existence  is 
recognized  and  specified  as  in  like  manner  such  ultimate  data.  His 
whole  contention  concerning  substances  is,  "  that  the  mind  of  man,, 
in  making  its  complex  ideas  of  substances,  never  puts  any  together 
that  do  not  really  and  are  not  supposed  to  co-exist;  and  so  it  truly 
borrows  that  union  from  nature."  6  They  directly  imply,  not  only 
simple  ideas,  but  their  "  constant  and  regular  union,"  or  order,  as 
well.  Without  the  admitted  perception  of  such  "  order,"  no  com- 
plex ideas  of  substances  are  possible,  whereby  the  "  chimerical  and 
fantastical "  can  distinguish  itself  from  "  the  real."  But  the  sec- 
ondary qualities  make  no  provision  for  such  data  as  herein  specified, 
not  any  more  so  than  they  do  for  the  perception  of  difference  or 
agreement,  the  ultimate  principle,  with  Locke,  of  all  knowledge. 
It  implies  comparison,  and  for  a  comparison  "  there  must  always  be 
in  relation  two  ideas  or  things,  either  in  themselves  really  separate, 
or  considered  as  distinct,  and  then  a  ground  or  occasion  for  their 
comparison."  7 

Now  all  such  admitted  data,  like  Locke's  distinction  between 
primary  and  secondary  qualities,  in  the  aspect  of  the  former  as 
simple  ideas,  involve  a  transcendence  of  the  secondary  qualities  as 
the  sole  data  of  knowledge.  When  Locke  therefore  admits  that 
"  it  is  evident  that  the  mind  knows  not  things  immediately,  but 
only  by  intervention  of  the  ideas  it  has  of  them,"  8  it  is  one  thing 
to  make  such  a  statement  from  the  standpoint  of  the  secondary 
qualities  as  constituting  our  sole  range  of  ideas,  and  quite  another 
to  make  it  from  the  standpoint  of  such  data  widened  in  its  scope, 
as  he  commonly  recognizes.  If  this  issue,  then,  of  an  unknown 
Ding  an  sicli  is  pertinent  from  the  former  standpoint,  no  problem 
may  seem  more  silly  from  the  latter.  Let  us  turn  to  the  problem 
from  the  standpoint  of  the  Ding  an  sich. 

Here  we  have  Locke's  issue  between  the  real  and  the  nominal 
essence.  The  real  essence  of  an  object  with  Locke  betokens  three  dis- 
tinct conceptions  as  bound  up  with  three  distinct  motives,  con- 
veniently describable  as  the  rationalistic,  the  sensationalistic,  and 

6.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sec.  29. 

7.  Bk.  II,  ch.  25,  sec.  6.    See  the  whole  of  this  chapter. 

8.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  4. 


32 

the  term-relation  motives.  Under  the  influence  of  the  rationalistic 
motive,  Locke's  conception  of  the  real  essence  of  an  object  grows 
out  of  the  demand  for  an  inherent  principle  in  objects,  in  virtue 
of  which  objects  attain  to  a  necessary  and  precise  determination 
of  the  number  and  the  kind  of  simple  ideas  composing  them ;  "  the 
reason  whereof  is  plain:  for  how  can  we  be  sure  that  this  or  that 
quality  is  in  gold  when  we  know  not  what  is  or  is  not  gold?" 
Without  knowledge  of  such  principle,  we  can  have  no  object  in  the 
strict  sense  of  the  word.  Each  substance  would  present  sheer 
diversit}r,  or,  if  held  as  determined  and  of  this  or  that  sort,  variety 
of  determination  in  each  sort  would  be  the  inevitable  outcome,  and, 
logically  considered,  each  sort  equally  valid  in  its  different  deter- 
mination. Have  we  such  ideas  of  substances  as  the  necessity  of  the 
case  would  seem  to  demand  ? — ideas  from  which  their  qualities  and 
properties  "  would  be  deducible  and  their  necessary  connection 
known,  as  all  the  properties  of  a  triangle  depend  on,  and v  as  far  as 
they  are  discoverable,  are  deducible  from  the  complex  idea  of  three 
lines,  including  a  space  ?  " 9  Locke's  answer  to  this  question  in 
its  endless  repetition,  never  contradicts  itself :  "  the  complex  ideas 
we  have  of  substances  are  certain  collections  of  simple  ideas  that 
have  been  observed  or  supposed  constantly  to  exist  together.  But 
such  a  complex  idea  cannot  be  the  real  essence  of  any  substance. 
.  .  .  This  essence,  from  which  all  these  properties  flow  (as  in  the 
case  of  gold),  when  I  inquire  into  it  and  search  after  it,  I  plainly 
perceive  I  cannot  discover;  the  furthest  I  can  go  is,  only  to  pre- 
sume that,  it  being  nothing  but  body,  its  real  essence  or  internal 
constitution,  on  which  these  qualities  depend,  c^n  be  nothing  but 
the  figure,  size  and  connection  of  its  solid  parts ;  of  neither  of  which 
having  any  distinct  perception  at  all,  can  I  have  any  idea  of  its 
essence,  which  is  the  cause  that  it  has  that  particular  shining  yel- 
lowness, a  greater  weight  than  anything  I  know  of  the  same  bulk, 
and  a  fitness  to  have  its  color  changed  by  the  touch  of  quicksilver. 
If  any  one  will  say  that  the  real  essence  and  internal  constitution 
on  which  these  properties  depend,  is  not  the  figure,  size,  and 
arrangement  or  connection  of  its  solid  parts,  but  something  else, 
...  I  am  even  further  from  having  any  idea  of  its  real  essence 
than  I  was  before."  10  In  either  event,  we  deal  with  a  '  supposi- 
tion' only,  and  one  that  Locke  regards  '  useless,' X1  from  the  stand- 
point under  consideration.  Substances  consist  of  the  nominal 

9.  Bk.  II,  ch.  31,  sec.  6. 

10.  Ibid. 

11.  Ibid.,  sec.  8. 


33 

essence  only.  I  shall  return  to  this  matter  in  a  later  chapter,  when 
considering  Locke's  counter  contention  that  modes  do  have  and 
reveal  such  real  essences;  in  which  contrast,  to  use  Kant's  termi- 
nology, substances  distinguish  themselves  from  modes  as  respect- 
ively aposteriori  and  apriori  determinable. 

From  the  standpoint  of  the  sensationalistic  motive,  wherein  the 
nominal  essence  is  identified  in  scope  with  the  secondary  qualities, 
Locke  sets  up  his  contrast  between  simple  ideas  as  consisting  of 
sensible  qualities  and  an  unknown  cause  consisting  of  insensible 
parts.  It  is  at  this  juncture  that  the  primary  qualities  are  com- 
pelled to  assume  their  dual  role;  they  are  thought  that  in  which 
"  our  senses  fail  us,"  and  yet  he  is  inclined  to  view  them  as  mere 
distinctions  within  simple  ideas.  They  are  made  to  pass  for  simple 
ideas  until  forced  to  function  as  insensible  parts,  whereupon 
"the  secondary  qualities  are  nothing  but  powers  depending  on 
its  primary  qualities."  But  whether  narrowly  or  widely  defined, 
with  Locke  the  nominal  essence,  as  the  knowable,  is  always  opposed 
to  the  real  essence  as  the  unknowable;  and  in  this  motive,  the  real 
essence  is  our  ontological  particular.  Hence,  if  the  primary  qual- 
ities persist  in  such  identification,  the  same  fate  would  naturally  be 
theirs  that  Locke,  without  exception,  visits  upon  the  real  essences 
in  general. 

But  if  real  essences  remain  unknown  from  either  of  the  above 
viewpoints  in  Locke,  from  the  standpoint  of  the  term-relation 
motive,  Locke  goes  a  step  further  and  holds  them  as  non-existent. 
According  to  this  motive  the  meaning  of  the  real  essence  is  identi- 
fied with  "  that  particular  constitution  which  everything  has  within 
itself,  without  any  relation  to  anything  without  it."  Here  again 
he  denies  the  existence  of  any  such  essence.  He  does  so  in  three 
distinct  ways.  I  quote  from  the  text  in  order  to  get  the  first  way 
stated.  "  It  is  evident  the  internal  constitution,  whereon  their  (an 
object's)  properties  depend,  is  unknown  to  us;  for  to  go  no  further 
than  the  grossest  and  most  obvious  of  objects  we  can  imagine 
amongst  them,  what  is  that  texture  of  parts,  that  real  essence,  that 
makes  lead  and  antimony  fusible,  wood  and  stones  not?  What 
makes  lead  and  iron  malleable,  antimony  and  stones  not  ?  "  12  That 
is  to  say,  objects  manifest  genuine  differences,  differences  hardly 
to  be  explained  where  we  abandoned  the  ultimate  character  of 
terms  entirely  and  expect  mere  relations  to  originate  such  differ- 
ences ;  yet  he  concludes,  that  the  supposed  essence  "  whereon  this 
difference  in  their  properties  depend,  is  unknown  to  us." 

12.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sec.  9. 


34 

Objects  resolve  themselves  into  nothing  but  "  powers  " — is  the 
second  and  more  familiar  way  in  which  this  term-relation  motive 
gets  itself  formulated  by  him.  I  select  a  passage  at  random :  "  The 
simple  ideas  that  make  up  our  complex  ideas  of  substances,  when 
truly  considered,  are  nothing  but  powers,  however  we  are  apt  to 
take  them  for  positive  qualities  ...  all  which  ideas  are  nothing 
else  but  so  many  relations  to  other  substances,  and  are  not  really 
in  the  gold  (to  take  an  instance),  considered  barely  in  itself,  though 
they  depend  on  those  real  and  primary  qualities  of  its  internal 
constitution."  13  His  disposition,  which  is  general,  (a)  to  resolve 
substances  into  pure  relation,  (b)  and  yet  not  to  do  so  out  of  a 
need  adequately  to  provide  for  inherent  differences  in  objects ;  and 
then  (c)  to  save  himself,  to  affirm  an  unknown  inner  constitution, 
(d)  which  in  turn  gets  itself  denied  as  a  reality  and  a  more  or  less 
"useless  supposition,"  is  the  circle  of  thought  in  which  he  keeps 
eternalty  revolving.  Where  doubt,  however,  still  persists  in  his 
mind  concerning  the  reality  of  an  inner  constitution  or  real  essence, 
the  next  line  of  reasoning  he  falls  back  upon,  according  to  his  own 
statement,  puts  the  matter  conclusively  and  beyond  all  doubt:  real 
essences  do  not  even  justify  the  mere  supposition  of  their  reality. 
It  involves  a  statement  of  the  relativistic  principle  in  its  so-called 
radical  form.  "  Put  a  piece  of  gold  anywhere  by  itself,  separate 
from  the  reach  and  influence  of  all  other  bodies,  it  will  immediately 
lose  all  its  color,  weight,  etc.  .  .  .Water,  in  which  to  us  fluidity 
is  an  essential  quality,  left  to  itself,  would  cease  to  be  fluid.  .  .  . 
We  are  then  quite  out  of  the  way  when  we  think  that  things  contain 
within  themselves  the  qualities  that  appear  to  us  in  them;  and  we 
in  vain  search  for  that  (inherent)  constitution  .  .  .  upon  which 
depend  those  qualities  and  powers  we  observe  in  them."  14  Viewed 
in  one  light  then,  substances  out  of  all  relations,  reduce  to  zero; 
viewed  in  the  other  light,  "  no  one  can  doubt,"  he  holds,  "  that 
this  called  gold  has  infinite  other  properties  not  contained  in  any 
specific  complex  idea  "  15  we  may  have  of  it.  The  following  quo- 
tation, however,  I  take  as  more  truly  representative  of  Locke  in  this 
term-relation  motive :  "  The  simple  qualities  which  make  up  the 
complex  ideas  being  most  of  them  powers  in  relation  to  changes 
which  they  are  apt  to  make  in  or  receive  from  other  '  bodies,'  are 
almost  infinite."  16  From  which  his  conclusion  follows,  that  if 

13.  Bk.  II,  ch.  23,  sec.  37. 

14.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  6,  sec.  11. 

15.  Bk.  II,  ch.  31,  sec.   10.     Italics  are  mine. 

16.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  9,  sec.  13. 


35 

essences  exist,  such  essences,  and  such  meaning  as  they  denote,  must 
be  found  within  the  nominal  essence;  the  nominal  essence,  in  the 
course  of  the  process,  ever  widening  its  data  beyond  the  secondary 
qualities  as  the  sole  ultimates. 

We  speak  in  general  as  if  ideas  (whether  simple  or  complex) 
were  determined  into  this  or  that  specific  determination  by  this  or 
that  specific  thing  actually  existing  as  one,  considering  the  specific 
things,  as  thus  indicated,  as  of  a  fixed  and  inherent  '  measure  and 
boundary '  ;  whereas,  according  to  Locke,  it  is  just  the  reverse  that 
is  true.  It  is  specific  ideas  in  specific  union  in  varying  situations 
that  give  a  specific  determination  to  our  abstract  ideas,  and,  accord- 
ing to  the  variety  and  differences  actually  existing  among  our  ideas, 
do  we  find  and  prescribe  variety  and  differences  in  the  determina- 
tion and  in  the  number  of  our  objects :  "  every  distinct  abstract 
idea  is  a  distinct  essence."  Water,  when  frozen,  we  designate  as  a 
distinct  thing  from  water  in  its  proper  form,  naming  it  ice.  Why 
do  we  fail  to  do  the  same  thing  in  the  case  of  gold  when  a  liquid 
and  when  a  solid,  or  with  jelly  when  a  liquid  and  when  congealed? 
Here,  then,  in  Locke's  claim  that  the  idea  determines  the  thing  and 
not  the  reverse,  we  have  (in  Kant's  familiar  phrase  in  its  familiar 
setting)  a  complete  Copernican  shift  in  our  view  of  things.  Locke's 
dogma:  "nothing  exists  but  particulars,"  thus  finds  its  other  ex- 
treme contention  in  him :  "  nothing  essential  to  particulars."  I 
have  already  suggested  his  resolution  of  the  matter.  It  is  based 
upon  an  empirical  relativity  and  a  synthetic  process  of  thought, 
culminating  in  what  may  be  termed  his  "  new  way  of  ideas  " ;  in 
the  course  of  which  process  the  real  essence,  as  defined  within  his 
rationalistic  motive,  gets  itself  transferred  to  the  nominal  essence. 
Hence  the  reason  for  terming  the  nominal  essence,  an  essence. 


CHAPTER  VI 

LOCKE'S  CONCEPTION"  OF  RELATION 

A  TERM  used  so  freely  in  Locke  as  relation,  demands  definition. 
What  does  Locke  understand  by  this  term  ?  The  question  is  not  to 
be  answered  off-hand,  nor,  after  due  inquiry,  to  be  answered  dog- 
matically. If  we  take  Hume's  version  of  it,  Locke  therein  denotes 
what  in  itself  were  a  delusion.  Knowledge  begins  with  impressions. 
What,  then,  is  the  impression  to  which  I  can  point  as  the  impres- 
sion of  a  relation?  And  his  conclusion  is,  as  we  know,  that  there 
are  no  such  existing  impressions,  and  that  relations,  accordingly, 
are  fictitious,  or,  at  best,  an  arbitrary  or  subjective  importation 
into  knowledge.  This  proclamation  in  Hume  has  its  equally  'full 
proclamation  in  Locke.  We  read  in  Locke  with  endless  repetition, 
that  whether  we  consider  objects  in  relation  to  objects  or  ideas  in 
relation  to  ideas,  at  no  point  can  we  perceive  a  visible  or  necessary 
connection  between  them,  except  among  one  class  of  ideas  only, — 
modes  as  a  priori  determinate.  "  How  any  thought  should  pro- 
duce a  motion  in  body  is  as  remote  from  the  nature  of  our  ideas, 
as  how  any  body  should  produce  any  thought  [simple  ideas]  in  the 
mind.  That  it  is  so,  if  experience  did  not  convince  us,  the  con- 
sideration of  the  things  themselves  would  never  be  able  in  the  least 
to  discover  to  us.  These,  and  the  like,  though  they  have  a  constant 
and  regular  connection  [co-existence  or  sequence]  in  the  ordinary 
course  of  things,  yet  the  connection  being  not  discoverable  in  the 
ideas  themselves  .  .  .  we  can  attribute  their  connection  to  nothing 
else  but  the  arbitrary  determination  of  that  All-wise  Agent." 1 
Yet  Locke,  notwithstanding,  devotes  chapters  to  "  ideas  "  of  rela- 
tions ;  speaks  of  a  "  visible  connection  "  in  respect  to  modes ;  and, 
in  respect  to  our  complex  ideas  of  substances,  writes  that,  "  when 
truly  considered  [such  ideas]  are  only  powers  .  .  .  nothing  else 
but  so  many  relations  to  other  substances."  2  And,  then,  in  his 

1.  Bk.  IV,  eh.  3,  sec.  28. 

2.  Bk.  II,  ch.  24,  sees.  6-12  and  37. 

36 


37 

chapter  on  "  powers "  we  read  this  very  remarkable  summary  of 
his  whole  position.  It  is  so  significant,  yet  brief,  that  I  quote  it 
in  full.  "I  confess  powers  includes  in  it  some  kind  of  relation, 
as  indeed,  which  of  our  ideas,  of  what  kind  soever,  when  attentively 
considered,  does  not?  For  our  ideas  of  extension,  duration,  and 
number,  do  they  not  all  contain  in  them  a  secret  relation  of  the 
parts?  Figure  and  motion  have  something  relative  in  them  much 
more  visibly;  and  sensible  qualities,  what  are  they  but  the  powers 
of  different  bodies,  in  relation  to  our  perception?  And,  if  con- 
sidered in  the  things  themselves,  do  they  not  depend  on  the  bulk, 
figure,  texture,  and  motion  of  the  parts?  All  which  include  some 
kind  of  relation  in  them.  Our  idea  therefore  of  power,  I  think., 
may  well  have  a  place  amongst  .other  simple  ideas,  and  be  con- 
sidered as  one  of  them."  3  That  is,  all  ideas  reduce  to  relations ; 
yet  that  seems  not  to  hinder  them  from  being  ideas;  yes,  even 
simple  ideas,  according  to  Locke. 

There  is  only  one  place  in  the  treatise,  that  I  can  recall,  where 
Locke  himself  deliberately  sets  about  to  define  the  term.  "  Kela- 
tion,  what  ?  " — is  the  title  of  the  Section.4  This  sounds  propitious ; 
let  us  turn  to  it.  There  we  read : — 

"  Besides  the  ideas,  whether  simple  or  complex,  that  the  mind 
has  of  things,  as  they  are  in  themselves,  there  are  others  it  gets 
from  their  comparison  one  with  another.  .  .  .  When  the  mind  so 
considers  one  thing,  that  it  does,  as  it  were,  bring  it  to  and  set  it 
by  another,  and  carries  its  view  from  one  to  the  other:  that  is, 
as  the  words  import,  relation  and  respect.  .  .  .  And  since  any 
idea,  whether  simple  or  complex,  may  be  the  occasion  why  the 
mind  thus  brings  two  things  together,  and,  as  it  were,  takes  a  view 
of  them  at  once,  though  still  considered  as  distinct;  therefore  any 
of  our  ideas  may  be  the  foundation  of  relation.  .  .  .  For  as  I 
said,"  he  adds  in  a  following  section,  "relation  is  a  way  of  com- 
paring or  considering  two  things  together,  and  giving  one  or  both 
some  appellation  (  'denomination ')  from  that  comparison;  and 
sometimes  giving  even  the  relation  itself  a  name  "  ;5  as  a  result  of 
which,  Locke  mentions,  as  some  among  the  " innumerable  kinds" 
of  relations,  causal,  spatial,  temporal,  quantitative,  qualitative, 
blood,  legal,  civic,  moral 6  etc. ;  and  that  objects,  in  view  of  their 
consideration  under  this  or  that  relation,  take  on  this  or  that  dis- 

3.  Ibid.,  ch.  21,  sec.  3.     Italics  are  mine. 

4.  Ibid.,  ch.  25,  sec.  1. 

5.  Ibid.,  sec.  1  and  6. 

6.  Ibid.,  ch.  26-28. 


38 

tinction  or  denomination,  "  although  it  be  not  contained  in  the 
real  (' positive  or  absolute')  existence  of  things,  but  is  something 
extraneous  or  superinduced." T  Thus  Locke,  upon  the  basis  of 
some  real  or  fancied  uniformities  or  continuities,  concedes  to 
thought  the  capacity  to  organize  our  objects  into  a  world  where 
mutual  implication  and  abstract  dependence  may  come  to  reveal  a 
whole  set  of  new  distinctions  (denominations)  in  our  objects;  but 
they  are  distinctions  which  exist  through  thought  and  for  thought 
only,  and  this  conclusion  Locke  insists  upon  over  and  over  again: 
they  are  merely  superinductions ;  they  in  no  way  alter,  modify,  or 
transform  the  things  themselves;  thought  and  facts  have  no  com- 
merce ;  "  nothing  really  exists  but  particulars." 

Our  first  conclusion,  then,  in  answer  to  the  question :  "relations 
what  ? "  stands  out  sharply :  relations  are  the  pure  products  of 
thought,  and  result  from  comparing  one  object  with  another;  but 
since  nothing  but  particulars,  by  dogma,  are  real;  and,  further, 
since  particulars,  by  dogma,  in  their  determination,  are  wholly 
independent  of  thought  and  its  processes,  relations  in  that  sense  are 
not  only  non-real  and  non-existent,  but  are  a  deliberate  and  specious 
falsification  of  reality, — Locke's  reality  as  ontological  particulars. 

But  are  they  the  pure  products  of  thought?  If  so,  why  speak 
of  a  necessity  enjoined  upon  the  mind  in  the  presence  of  change 
"  to  collect  a  power  somewhere  "  to  account  for  it,  if  no  such  thing 
as  necessity  exists?  Or  where  does  that  necessity  arise  if  wholly 
irrelevant  to  particulars?  Do  causality,  space,  time,  and  morality 
exist,  or  not?  Are  they  something,  or  mere  nothing?  They  are 
some  of  his  typical  relations;  but  what  is  their  status  and  part  in 
the  scheme  of  things  ?  Then  again,  if  relations  are  pure  products 
of  thought,  why  designate  the  "  relations  "  pertaining  to  modes  as 
"  visible,"  and  those  pertaining  to  substances  <c  undiscoverable  "  ? 
If  relations  are  non-existent  and  invisible  as  fact-reality  within  the 
sphere  of  substances,  just  what  is  that  "  visible  "  relation  affirmed 
by  Locke  as  existent  within  the  sphere  of  modes?  Is  the  relation 
element  in  this  latter  sphere  "  visible  "  solely  because  in  this  sphere, 
as  Locke  inclines  to  preserve  it,  its  facts  are  equally  as  visible  or 
invisible :  so  that  "  visible "  in  this  sphere  is  equivalent  to  the 
"  invisible  "  in  the  sphere  of  substances  ?  Then  if  so,  what  right  has 
Locke  to  identify  the  higher  type  of  knowledge  and  reality  with 
modes,  as  he  does  in  Book  IV,  where  he  specifically  deals  with  the 
matter,  and  to  identify  a  disrupted  and  makeshift  sort  of  reality 
with  substances,  the  whole  issue  there  determined  by  this  affirmed 

7.  Ibid.,  ch.  25,  sec.  8. 


39 

difference  in  the  kind  of  their  relations?  These  questions  are 
exceedingly  pertinent.  Let  us  see  whether  an  answer  to  them  is 
accessible  in  Locke,  keeping  in  mind,  however,  that  our  present 
problem  is  merely  to  get  at  Locke's  full  conception  of  the  term  rela- 
tion. Other  issues  will  abide  their  proper  place  and  time. 


THE  VISIBLE  RELATIONS  OF  MODES:     WHAT  IS  THEIR  KIND;    WHAT 

THEIR  REALITY 

We  may  roam  at  large  in  Book  IV,  and  almost  on  every  page 
we  will  find  ourselves  confronted  by  the  statement  that  modes  are 
essentially  different  from  substances ;  the  former  pertaining  wholly 
to  reason,  and  are  its  offsprings;  the  latter  pertaining  wholly  to 
experience,  as  divorced  from  reason,  and  in  turn  wholly  its  off- 
springs. Then  we  will  also  habitually  encounter  there,  the  uncrit- 
icized  and  unanalyzed  assertion  that  the  "  relations  "  of  the  one  are 
"  visible,"  and  the  copiously  criticized  and  analyzed  fact  that  the 
relations  of  the  other  are  totally  invisible.  Such  is  the  situation. 
A  passage  or  two  from  the  text  will  suffice  our  purpose. 

"  Is  it  true  of  the  ideas  of  a  triangle  that  its  three  angles  are 
equal  to  two  right  ones?  Then  it  is  true  also  of  a  triangle, 
wherever  it  really  exists.  Whatever  other  figure  exists,  that  is  not 
exactly  answerable  to  the  idea  of  a  triangle  in  his  mind,  is  not  at 
all  concerned  in  that  proposition;  and  therefore  he  is  certain  all 
his  knowledge  concerning  such  ideas  is  real  knowledge;  because, 
intending  things  no  further  than  they  agree  with  those  his  ideas, 
he  is  sure  what  he  knows  concerning  those  figures,  when  they  have 
barely  an  ideal  existence  in  his  mind,  will  hold  true  of  them  also 
when  they  have  real  existences  in  matter."  8 

The  passage  is  a  very  compact  statement  of  his  doctrine  of 
a  priori  modes,  and  the  doctrine  is  a  fixture  in  Locke.  Its  outcome : 
reality  identified  with  ideality,  and  because  alone  fulfilling  his 
conceived  requirements  of  knowledge  proper  (that  which  is  not 
mere  opinion)  identified  by  him  with  reality  in  its  most  perfect 
form.  These  generalities  aside,  let  us  get  down  to  particulars. 

The  doctrine,  in  the  first  place,  asserts  a  certain  independence  in 
our  thought  activity,  capable  of  forming  ideas,  not  directly  depend- 
ing upon  sense,  nor  directly  responsible  to  it,  and,  within  its  own 
province,  having  as  it  were,  its  own  codes,  patterns,  and  standards 
of  reality.  Hence  if  moral  knowledge  is  the  knowledge  of  modes, 

8.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  4,  sec.  6. 


40 

and  the}:,  "  as  other  modes,  be  of  our  own  making,  what 
strange  notions  will  there  be  of  justice  and  temperance !  No  con- 
fusion at  all/7  for  in  the  case  of  morality  as  in  the  case  of  the 
triangle,  as  he  goes  on  to  say,  "  we  intend  things  no  further  than 
as  they  are  conformable  to  our  ideas,'5  9  and  if  things  are  not  con- 
formable, so  much  the  worse  for  them. 

"\Ve  may  grant  all  this  originating  power  of  thought  and  the 
reality  of  its  objects  as  thus  determined;  but  because  their  parts 
(because  more  highly  simplified  in  their  reality)  seem  more  coer- 
cive in  their  mutual  dependence  and  implication,  are  we  entitled  for 
that  reason  to  judge  these  relations  of  a  type  generically  distinct? 
Does  the  uniqueness  of  relation,  as  compared  with  fact-reality,  lose 
any  of  that  uniqueness  in  this  new  setting  of  them?  And  if  not, 
then  the  supposed  distinction  between  visible  and  invisible  rela- 
tions, as  one  of  kind,  vanishes,  and  only  one  question  more  remains 
to  be  answered.  Whence  that  necessity  that  leads  Reason  to  produce 
"its  modes,  such  as  they  are  ?  And  I  can  think  of  no  other  answer 
than  the  one  to  be  asserted  in  connection  with  the  other  type  of  rela- 
tions; namely,  the  necessity  resides  in  certain  uniformities,  and 
in  certain  "  constant  and  regular  union "  of  parts ;  and,  if  in 
response  to  the  demand  of  the  one  type  of  uniformities  and  union  of 
parts,  the  mind,  or  "  we  intend  things  no  further,"  does  it  follow 
that  we  or  the  mind  ought  not  to  "  intend  things  further  "  ?  Sup- 
pose we  determine  that  the  mind  should  "  intend  things  further," 
be}^ond  a  mere  contemplation  of  certain  abstract  ideas  with  their 
habitudes  and  relations;  or  suppose  a  mutual  sequence  observed 
among  substances,  forces  the  mind  "  to  collect  a  power  somewhere  " 
to  account  for  it;  are  we  to  suppose  the  uniformities  of  the  one 
sphere,  that  of  modes,  share  in  a  prerogative  which  makes  them 
more  real  or  binding,  than  the  uniformities  of  the  other  ?  And  are 
we  further  to  suppose,  that,  in  the  one  case,  our  objects  are,  there- 
fore, purely  a  product  of  the  mind;  and  objects,  in  the  case  of  sub- 
stances, purely  products  unaffected  by  thought, — Locke's  ontological 
particulars?  And  if  Locke  himself  does  not  allow  us  to  persist  in 
such  a  divorce,  shall  we  conclude  with  him,  that,  "  apart  from  our 
abstract  ideas,  no  determination  in  our  substances  is  possible  ?  "  10 
In  other  words,  shall  we  credit  Locke  with  the  justice  of  knowing 
his  own  mind  in  terming  his  philosophy  "  the  new  way  of  ideas  "  ? 
Further,  shall  we  credit  that  "  new  way  "  with  the  same  Coperni- 
can  inversion  of  object  and  idea,  that  Kant  credits  himself  with 

9.  Ibid.,  sec.  5  and  9. 

10.  Bk.  Ill,  eh.  6,  sees.  1-8. 


41 

originating?  Then  the  claim:  "identity  suited  to  the  idea  "n 
contains  bound  up  in  itself  the  deepest  utterance  from  Locke :  rela- 
tions are  generated  in  a  thought  situation  and  relate  to  every  object 
in  so  far  as  they  are  grasped  and  comprehended  by  thought;  and 
what  an  object  may  be  apart  from  such  a  thought  construct  of  it, — 
for  that  answer  we  must  turn  to  the  destructive  and  profitless 
analysis  of  a  Hume,  or  in  Locke  himself,  where  his  uncriticized 
dogmatism  throws  a  confusing  shadow  upon  his  brighter  vision, 
fully  elaborated  by  him  as  we  shall  come  to  see.  Hence,  in  his 
efforts  to  discover  where  the  unity  of  objects  in  general  lie,  physical, 
vegetative,  and  animal,  including  that  of  personal  identity,  he 
does  not  seek  to  find  a  "  real "  essence,  nor  an  empirical  unity  (an 
impression  in  Hume's  sense),  but  a  thought-constructed  and  a 
thought-determined  unity.  Relations  stand  for  determinations, 
abstract  or  concrete,  which  the  mind  feels  itself  privileged,  as  well 
as  constrained,  to  take  note,  in  any  effort  to  know  its  objects  and  to 
organize  them ;  beyond  which  end,  we  may  grant,  "  the  mind  need 
not  intend  things  further," — beyond  the  articulated  needs  of  an 
articulated  self  for  an  articulated  world.  Thus  does  his  ration- 
alistic motive,  by  stages,  get  itself  thoroughly  fused  with  his  pos- 
sivistic  motive.  It  reflects  itself  in  the  scope  accorded  by  Locke  to 
conduct,  to  the  nominal  essence,  and  to  synthesis. 

11.  Bk.  II,  ch.  27. 


Ill 

ANTI-RELATIVISTIC  MOTIVES  IN  LOCKE 

CHAPTER  Til 

IDEAS  versus  KNOWLEDGE  AXD  MEAXIXG 

THE  tendency  in  Locke  to  resolve  even  simple  ideas  into  rela- 
tions finds  a  counter  motive  in  him  making  df -ideas  the  self- 
sufficient  and  all  other  reality  a  mere  consequence.  Thus  Knowl- 
edge, in  his  restricted  sense  of  the  word,  "  is  founded  in  the  habi- 
tudes and  relations  of  abstract  ideas  " ;  *  Meaning  is  "  the  compar- 
ing or  considering  of  two  things  together,"  whereby  a  new  and 
irrelevant  type  of  reality  results,  commonly  designated  by  him  as 
equivalent  to  the  term  signification.  I  described  it  as  irrelevant. 
By  that  I  simply  mean  that  "  it  is  not  contained  in  the  real  exist- 
ence of  things  (the  original  ideas),  but  something  extraneous  and 
superinduced."  2  It  is  to  this  self-sufficient  and  originating  char- 
acter of  our  ideas,  in  their  affirmed  independence  of  relations  to 
which  I  wish  now  to  draw  attention.  Upon  what  ground  does  he 
rest  this  contention? 

"  To  improve  our  knowledge,"  says  Locke,  "  is,  I  think,  to  get 
and  fix  in  our  minds  clear,  distinct  and  complete  ideas  .  .  .  and 
thus,  perhaps,  without  any  other  principle,  but  barely  considering 
those  perfect  ideas,  and  by  comparing  them  one  with  another,  find- 
ing their  agreement  or  disagreement,  and  their  several  relations 
and  habitudes,  we  shall  get  more  true  and  clear  knowledge  by  the 
conduct  of  this  one  rule  than  by  taking  in  principles,  and  thereby 
putting  our  minds  into  the  disposal  of  others.'' 3  If  our  ideas  are 
to  be  "  clear  and  complete  "  before  they  enter  into  relations,  the 

1.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  12,  sec.  7. 

2.  Bk.  II,  ch.  25,  sec.  8. 

3.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  12,  sec.  6. 

42 


43 

relations  could  scarcely  be  calculated  to  make  them  more  so.  The 
implication  is  evident:  ideas  or  terms  elaborate  themselves,  seek 
to  make  themselves  "clear  and  complete"  outside  of  the  knowl- 
edge or  relation  situation. 

This  whole  motive  crystallizes  itself  very  clearly  when  we  bring 
Locke's  triple  4  division  of  perception  into  mind ;  the  perception 
of  an  idea;  the  perception  of  "  a  visible  connection  "  (Knowledge)  ; 
and  the  perception  of  signification  (Meaning).  In  neither  case 
do  we  appear  to  get  beyond  a  "perception5';  and  the  difference 
between  them  is  one,  not  of  the  Understanding,  but  of  three  dis- 
tinct types  of  reality  thus  perceived.  Let  us,  if  possible,  get  at  the 
matter  from  its  very  roots. 

I  think  to  find  his  apotheosis  of  the  idea  to  issue  from  its  union 
of  his  two  sharply  antithetical  convictions, — his  possivistic  reac- 
tionary one:  nothing  exists  but  particulars;  and  his  rationalistic 
one,  that  certain  and  absolute  knowledge  involves  an  a  priori  deter- 
mination of  parts  and  their  mutual  and  inevitable  implication/ 
Subsequently  the  former  conviction,  dogmatic  in  form,  gets  itself 
transformed  into  or  substituted  by  his  critical  view,  that  simple 
ideas  constitute  our  ultimates.  The  simple  ideas  in  turn  unite 
themselves  with  the  rationalistic  criterion  of  truth  which  centers 
itself  in  "  clear  and  distinct "  ideas.  Nor  is  there  any  effort  on 
Locke's  part  to  consider  simple  ideas  as  otherwise  than  synonymous 
with  "  clear  and  distinct "  ideas ;  and  if  either  motive  gains  the 
ascendancy,  it  is  the  rationalistic  one.  Consider  his  general  account 
of  what  constitutes  the  unity  of  our  simple  ideas ;  namely,  "  that  it 
be  considered  as  one  representation  or  picture  in  the  mind/'  which 
account  gets  itself  stated  in  the  very  opening  chapters  of  Book  II 
and  repeats  itself  without  modification  throughout  the  Essay. 
Particulars,  simple  ideas,  clear  and  distinct  ideas,  and  a  priori  ideas 
—these  four  prescribe  the  locus  of  a  distinct  phase  of  his  thought. 
Each  in  turn,  or  the  four  in  fusion,  as  the  case  may  be,  pretend 
to  what  is  final  and  ultimate  in  reality.  They  need  nothing  to 
make  them  more  "  perfect  and  complete " ;  they  are  perfect  and 
complete  in  themselves ;  and  knowledge  and  meaning,  either  irrele- 
vant incidents  to  them,  or  necessary  consequences  of  them ;  knowl- 
edge and  meaning  thus  issuing  forth  as  two  new  and  distinct 
types  of  reality,  which,  if  any  sort  of  reality  at  all,  must,  like  ideas 
in  general,  be  modes  of  perception.  Thus,  in  his  reaction  to  "  abuse 
of  words,"  he  sends  us  for  remed}7^  to  "  clear  and  distinct "  ideas, 

4.  See  Bk.  II,  ch.  21,  sec.  5. 


4A 

and  likewise  in  his  re-action  to  authority  or  general  principles  and 
maxims  of  all  land.  That  he  should  also  have  been  driven  to  the 
same  source  for  knowledge  (such  as  his  notion  of  knowledge  is) 
seems  inevitable.  Thus  we  read  that  ideas  are  not  dependent  upon, 
or  the  consequence  of,  the  knowledge  situation,  but  "  knowledge 
is  the  consequence  of  the  ideas  (be  they  what  they  will)  that  are 
in  our  minds  .  .  .  that  wherever  we  can  suppose  such  a  creature 
as  man  is,  endowed  with  such  faculties,  and  thereby  furnished 
with  such  ideas  as  we  have,  we  conclude,  he  must  needs  when  he 
applies  his  thoughts  to  the  consideration  of  his  ideas,  know  the 
truth  of  certain  propositions  that  will  arise  from  the  agreement 
or  disagreement  which  he  will  perceive  in  his  own  ideas."  5  The 
"  neAv  way  of  ideas "  does  not  characterize  his  doctrine  amiss 
whether  we  consider  this  motive  in  his  thinking  or  whether  we 
consider  the  far  more  approved  and  developed  ones.  But  we  must 
not  fail  to  note,  that  as  a  matter  of  general  theory  with  him,  it  is 
primarily  the  "  way  of  ideas  "  to  knowledge,  and  not  primarily  the 
"  way  of  ideas  "  to  objects;  and  yet  objects,  in  their  characterization 
of  modes  and  substances,  are  the  central  interest  with  him.  Fail- 
ing, as  he  does,  to  make  the  idea  dependent  upon  its  relations, 
even  while  making  the  relations  dependent  upon,  although  wholly 
external  to,  ideas,  the  knowledge  said  to  result  really  gets  itself 
set  up  as  an  entirely  new  thing.  Hence  to  keep  knowledge  and 
objects  apart,  or  to  make  of  knowledge  an  end  independent  of 
objects,  is  an  antithesis  in  Locke  that  yields  nothing  but  contra- 
diction and  confusion  till  we  come  to  his  doctrine  of  "  Sorts  "  in 
Book  III.  Influenced  by  his  mistaken  notion  of  knowledge,  his 
aim  in  Book  II  is  not  to  consider  his  simple  ideas,  as  essentially 
determinations  of  things,  but  as  the  elements  "out  of  which  is 
made  all  its  other  knowledge.''' c  Or,  with  clear  and  distinct  ideas 
the  touchstone  of  reality,  simple  ideas  become  the  means  of  apprais- 
ing knowledge,  such  as  it  is :  he  demands  any  one  to  produce  a  com- 
plex idea,  which,  in  so  far  as  it  is  valid,  is  "  not  made  out  of  those 
simple  ideas." 

Let  us  consider  this  matter  in  a  slightly  different  light;  and 
this  were  best  done  by  considering  the  matter  from  the  standpoint 
of  a  proposition  or  predication.  It  will  guard  against  the  con- 
viction that  Locke's  definition  of  knowledge,  as  the  agreement  of 
disagreement  of  ideas,  is  mere  jingle,  and  provide  against  the 

5.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  11,  sec.  14.    Italics  are  mine. 

6.  Bk.  II,  ch.  7,  sec.  10. 


opposite  conviction  that  true  predication  is  therein*  involved  or 
understood. 

There  are  two  sorts  of  general  propositions,  .says  Locke,  the 
truth  of  which,  it  is  affirmed,  we  get  to  know  with  perfect  certainty. 
"  The  one  is,  of  those  trifling  propositions  [otherwise  called, 
analytical  or  explicative  propositions]  which  have  a  certainty  in 
them,  but  it  is  only  a  verbal  certainty,  but  not  instructive.  And, 
secondly,  we  can  know  the  truth  and  so  may  be  certain  in  proposi- 
tions, which  affirm  something  of  another,  which  is  a  necessary  con- 
sequence of  its  precise  complex  idea,  but  not  contained  in  it:  as 
that  the  external  angles  of  all  triangles  is  bigger  than  either  of 
the  opposite  internal  angles."  7  Modes  are  said  to  yield  this  type 
of  instructive  propositions,  which  Locke  then  sets  up  in  radical 
contrast  to  all  general  propositions  based  on  substances,  as,  for 
example,  that  "  gold  is  yellow ; "  which,  if  they  are  certain,  are 
trifling;  and  if  instructive,  are  uncertain.8  We  have  trifling  prop- 
ositions, in  respect  to  substances,  "  when  a  part  of  the  complex 
idea  is  predicated  of  the  name  of  the  whole,"  as  "  when  the  genus 
is  predicated  of  the  species,  or  more  comprehensive  of  less  compre- 
hensive terms.  For  what  information,  what  knowledge,  carries 
this  proposition  in  it :  viz.,  Lead  is  a  metal,  to  a  man  who  knows 
the  complex  idea  the  name  lead  stands  for?  .  .  .  Indeed  to  a  man 
that  knows  the  signification  of  the  word  metal,  and  not  of  the  word 
lead,  it  is  a  shorter  way  to  explain  the  signification  of  the  word 
lead.  .  .  .  But,  before  a  man  makes  any  proposition,  he  is  sup- 
posed to  understand  the  terms  he  uses  in  it  [that  is,  he  is  sup- 
posed to  make  his  ideas  te  clear,  distinct,  complete,  and  perfect " 
before  they  enter  a  proposition  or  enter  the  knowledge  situation] 
or  else  he  talks  like  a  parrot,  and  making  a  noise  by  imitation  and 
framing  certain  sounds,  which  he  has  learnt  of  others;  but  not 
as  a  rational  creature,  using  them  for  signs  of  ideas  which  he  has 
in  his  mind  "  9  [If  only  he  would  evolve  them,  I  suppose.] 

This  passage  is  illuminating  and  throws  Locke's  whole  position 
in  full  relief.  All  reality  begins  and  ends  with  ideas;  that  pred- 
ication is  explication,  and  that  explication  (and,  hence,  predica- 
tion) does  not  realize  itself  as  a  fact,  save  where  ideas  are  already 
"  complete  and  perfect "  before  they  enter  or  attempt  to  enter  the 
knowledge  situation, — explication  and  knowledge  situation  being 
one  in  meaning;  that  entering  the  knowledge  situation  is  not  for 

7.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  8,  see.  8. 

8.  Ibid.,  sec.  9. 

9.  Ibid.,  sees.  4-7. 


46 

the  purpose  of  studying  objects  in  their  changing  value  or  character 
due  to  new  relations  to  other  objects  thus  noted,  discovered,  or 
forced  upon  them  (the  proper  role  of  predication,  fully  recognized 
in  his  account  of  Sorts),  but  that  predication  is  merely  an  explica- 
tion of  what  already  exists  in  a  completed  form  or  gets  thus  to 
exist,  but  in  and  through  some  inner  developing  or  dynamic  motive 
of  their  own,  and  wholly  outside  of  the  knowledge  situation. 

Here  then  in  Locke  we  have  his  one,  seriously  to  be  considered 
anti-relativistic  motive.  The  importance,  or  rather,  prominence 
of  the  contention  with  him  demands,  in  the  first  place,  that  we 
inquire  more  narrowly  into  this  a  priori  claim.  For,  as  this  claim 
implies,  ideas  (objects)  are  not  products  involving  relations  and 
knowledge.  Inquiry  into  this  -  contention  constitutes  the  subject- 
matter  of  the  next  chapter.  It  suffices  to  observe  here,  that  even 
though  knowledge  and  meaning  are  taken  by  him  in  the  light  of 
"  extraneous  superinductions,"  this  claim  acquires  force  only  to 
the  extent  in  which  the  thought-process  appears  transferred  within 
the  periphery  of  the  ideas  themselves.  This  motive  in  Locke  is 
not  sensationalistic,  but  rationalistic  and  a  priori.  How  this  matter 
ultimately  gets  to  resolve  itself  in  his  pages,  our  future  chapters 
are  required  to  help  make  clear.  At  this  point,  however,  be  it  said, 
that  in  this  conceived  self-sufficient  character  of  our  ideas,  we  find 
in  him  the  one  extreme  anti-relativistic  motive,  and,  such  as  it  is, 
the  direct  opposite  of  his  general  contention,  that  ideas  or  objects 
are  nothing  but  "  powers,"  that  is,  relations. 


CHAPTER  VIII 


A  UNO  1. 1  T  I-     K  XOWLEDGE  I 


LOCKE'S  claim  of  an  absolute  knowledge  bulks  forth  with  large 
proportions,  giving  occasion  in  Book  IV  for  the  central  problem 
there  set  up  between  knowledge  proper  and  knowledge  as  mere 
Opinion  or  Judgments  of  Probability. 

The  distinction  made  rests  upon  the  assertion,  as  expressed  in 
Kantian  terminology,  that  certain  ideas  (modes)  are  a  priori  deter- 
minable,  and  others  (substances)  are  a  posteriori  determinable. 
Thus  he  writes :  "  In  some  of  our  ideas  there  are  certain  relations, 
habitudes,  and  connections,  so  visibly  included  in  the  nature  of 
the  ideas  themselves,  that  we  cannot  conceive  them  separable  from 
them  by  any  power  whatsoever.  And  in  these  only,  we  are  capable 
of  certain  and  universal  knowledge.  Thus  the  idea  of  a  right- 
lined  triangle  necessarily  carries  with  it  an  equality  of  its  angles 
to  two  right  ones.  Nor  can  we  conceive  this  relation,  this  connec- 
tion of  these  two  ideas  to  be  possibly  mutable,  or  to  depend  on 
any  arbitrary  power  which  of  choice  made  it  thus  or  could  make  it 
otherwise  " ;  *  whereas  in  respect  to  "  the  coherence  and  continuity 
of  the  parts  of  matter;  the  production  of  sensation  in  us  of  colors 
and  sounds,  etc.,  by  impulse  and  motion;  nay,  the  original  rules 
and  communication  of  motion  being  such  wherein  we  can  discover 
no  natural  connection  with  any  ideas  we  have,  we  cannot  but 
ascribe  them  to  the  arbitrary  will  and  good  pleasure  of  the  Wise 
Architect."  :  Ideas  of  the  latter  type,  when  joined  together  in  a 
proposition,  because  their  "  connection  and  dependencies,  being 
not  discoverable  in  our  ideas,  we  can  have  but  an  experimental 
knowledge  of  them/'  All  such  propositions  are  held  as  limited  in 
scope,  conditional  in  character,  and  full  of  uncertainty  and  pos-« 

1.  Bk.  IV,  eh.  8,  sec.  8.     Italics  are  mine. 

2.  Ibid.,  ch.  3,  sec.  29. 

47 


48 

sible  error.  "  Certainty  and  universality  "  in  knowledge  only  exists 
where,  "  by  the  mere  contemplation  of  any  of  our  ideas,"  I  am  able 
to  affirm  something  of  another  idea  "  which  is  a  necessary  conse- 
quence of  its  precise  complex  idea,  but  not  contained  in  it," : 
although  "  certainty "  without  "  universality "  is  attained  in  the 
other  types  of  ideas  in  our  judgments  of  "  particulars  " :  "  as  when 
our  senses  are  actually  employed  about  any  object,  we  do  know 
that  it  exists;  so  by  our  memory,  we  may  be  assured  that  hereto- 
fore things  that  effected  our  senses  have  existed."  4  But  judgments 
of  "  particulars  "  aside,  which  do  not  here  concern  us,  "  certainty 
and  universality  "  in  knowledge,  if  anything  more  than  verbal  or 
trifling,  is  possible  only  with  that  type  of  ideas  where,  as  stated, 
by  the  mere  contemplation  of  an  idea,  we  are  able  to  affirm  some- 
thing of  another  idea  "  which  is  a  necessary  consequence  of  its 
precise  complex  idea  but  not  contained  in  it."  Where  such  a  priori 
determination  of  an  idea  is  not  possible,  we  do  not  have  knowl- 
edge in  his  use  of  the  word,  as  identified  with  "  certainty  and 
universality,"  but  mere  "  opinion "  or  judgments  of  probability. 
Thus  considered  and  thus  distinguished,  he  regards  knowledge 
possible  only  in  respect  to  modes,  in  truth  whereof  mathematics  is 
cited  as  an  accomplished  fact,  and  "  demonstrated  morality  "  a  pet 
faith  and  conviction  of  his;  whereas  "propositions  that  are  made 
about  substances,  if  they  are  certain,  are  for  the  most  part  trifling ; 
and,  if  they  are  instructive,  are  uncertain,  and  such  as  we  can 
have  no  knowledge  of  their  real  truth,  however  much  constant  obser- 
vation and  analogy  may  assist  our  judgment  in  guessing."  5  The 
fact  of  this  distinction  in  Locke,  in  its  asserted  reality  and  in  its 
nature,  is  beautifully  summarized  in.  the  following  brief  citation. 
Further  citations  would  contain  little  more  than  a  monotonous 
variant  thereof.  He  writes :  "  The  want  of  ideas  of  their  real 
essences  sends  us  from  our  thoughts  to  the  things  themselves  as  they 
exist.  Experience  here  must  teach  me  what  reason  cannot." 6 
Relativity  will  be  found  the  outcome  of  both  aspects  of  this  doc- 
trine; latent  in  respect  to  modes;  explicit  in  respect  to  substances. 
It  is  necessary  to  add,  however,  that  substances  do  not  get  their 
full  and  proper  elaboration  from  him  in  Book  IV.  For  that  we 
must  turn  to  the  Chapter  on  Sorts.  And  the  same  may  be  said 

3.  Ibid.,  ch.  8,  sec,  8. 

4.  Ibid.,  ch.  11,  see.  11. 

5.  Ibid.,  ch.  8,  sec.  9.    Italics  are  mine. 

6.  Ibid.,  ch.  12,  sec.  9.    Italics  are  mine. 


49 

in  regard  to  modes ;  here,  the  former  gets  its  reality  despoiled ;  the 
latter,  assigned  a  reality  which  simulates  the  rejected  innate  ideas. 
Locke  distinguishes  between  them  in  two  respects. 

1.  Concerning  their  origin. 

2.  Concerning  their  foundation. 

1.  In  regard  to  origin,  modes  originate  with  or  in  the  mind, 
and,  in  their  quality,  present  the  status  of  "  real  "  essences ;  whereas 
substances  have  their  origin  in  the  simple  ideas,  and,  hence,  of  the 
so-called  "  nominal  "  ^essence  only. 

2.  In  regard  to  their  respective  foundation,  modes  are  held  as 
grounded  in  abstract  reason,  and  involve  for  their  certainty,   (a) 
"the  mere  evidence  of  the  thing  itself"  or   (b)  the  principle  of 
Inconceivability.     As  for  substances,  their  foundation  is  said  to  be 
experience  as  divorced  from  Reason. 


FOUNDATION   OF   MODES 

Locke  gives  the  matter  incidental  rather  than  deliberate  atten- 
tion. He  merely  speaks  of  a  "  visible  "  connection  between  certain 
of  our  ideas  and  the  lack  of  such  "  visible "  connection  among 
other  ideas ;  but  he  nowhere  attempts  to  articulate  what  this  asser- 
tion appears  to  involve.  Thus  he  writes  in  his  Third  Letter  to 
Still  ingneet :  "  To  perceive  the  agreement  or  disagreement  of  two 
ideas  and  not  to  perceive  the  agreement  or  disagreement  of  two 
ideas  is,  I  think,  a  criterion  to  distinguish  what  a  man  is  certain 
of  from  what  he  is  not  certain  of.  Has  your  Lordship  any  other 
or  better  criterion  to  distinguish  certainty  from  uncertainty?" 
That  mere  awareness  is  the  principle  here  involved,  seems  obvious. 
In  other  cases,  where  the  idea  of  a  rational  foundation  comes  to 
expression,  as  I  stated,  it  appears  to  be  the  principle  of  Incon- 
ceivability.6 One  additional  quotation  in  this  connection  must  also 
suffice.  "  We  cannot  conceive  the  relation,  the  connection  of  these 
two  ideas  (speaking  of  certain  parts  of  a  triangle),  to  be  possibly 
mutable,  or  to  depend  on  any  arbitrary  power  which  of  choice  made 
it  thus  or  could  make  it  otherwise."  They  stand  for  reason,  as  it 
were,  objectified  and  inherent  in  the  very  nature  of  this  class  of 
things.  But  as  Locke  was  seen  to  take  his  simple  ideas  more  or 
less  for  granted  (logical  data,  rather  than  psychological),  so  with 

6.  The  connection  between  ideas  of  the  a  priori  type  yield  a  ' '  certainty 
every  one  finds  to  be  so  great  that  he  cannot  imagine,  and  therefore  not 
require  a  greater."  Bk.  IV,  ch.  2,  sec.  1. 


50 

the  fact  of  consciousness  as  awareness  or  perception,  he  merely 
accepts  its  deliverance  as  a  fact  that  is  ultimate,  and  does  not,  save 
incidentally,  make  either  of  them  a  subject  of  special  inquiry.  Cer- 
tain connections  are  affirmed  by  him  as  "  visible/'  and  others  not, 
and  solely  because  "  visible "  claimed  by  him  to  be  underived, 
unconditioned,  and  final.  They  are  then  forthwith  accepted  and 
described  by  him  as  constituting  knowledge  that  is  absolute.  But 
when  we  inquire  into  this  alleged  distinction  within  connections, 
we  find  that  the  whole  matter  resolves  itself  into  the  claim  that 
in  certain  objects,  as  in  the  case  of  a  triangle,  parts  are  found 
mutually  and  inevitably  to  involve  and  implicate  each  other; 
whereas,  in  the  case  of  substance,  he  puts  himself  to  great  pains  to 
prove  that  the  direct  opposite  is  found  to  characterize  its  parts ; 
they  are  discrete  and  disparate,  without  rhyme  or  rhythm,  and 
at  no  time  permit  the  mind,  by  the  mere  contemplation  of  the 
one,  to  pass  to  the  other.  He  fails,  however,  in  this  affirmed  dis- 
tinction, to  take  note  of  three  significant  facts:  first,  that  the  tri- 
angle, like  any  other  object,  is  a  construct ;  secondly,  that  it  is  rela- 
tive to  the  mind,  whose  principle  of  self -evidence,  although  in 
itself  ultimate,  involves,  in  any  given  situation,  the  principle  of 
exclusion  or  inconceivability,  and  hence  is  inherently  relative  and 
conditioned,  whether  such  conditions  remain  fixed  or  changeable ; 
and  thirdly,  that  it  is  dependent  in  this  specific  instance,  upon  a 
derived  and  fixed  conception  of  space,  which  conception,  if  altered, 
would  subject  the  triangle  to  the  same  vicissitudes  of  change  that 
any  other  object  finds  itself  exposed  to  share.  Allowing  for  a  differ- 
ence in  degree,  I  can  see  no  reason  why  the  substance  gold,  as  a 
construct,  deliberately  held  fixed  to  the  exclusion  of  change,  should 
any  less  successfully  implicate  its  parts  than  is  claimed  of  the  parts 
of  a  triangle.  It  may  be  affirmed  of  the  triangle  that  its  sides 
implicate  the  angles  in  a  way  that  weight  and  the  color  of  my 
fixed  concept  of  gold  would  not  implicate  each  other.  But  in  these 
two  situations,  is  the  difference  at  bottom  any  other  than  the  fact 
that  the  principle  of  inconceivability  is  differently  involved?  I 
admit  a  difference  of  degree,  but  not  a  difference  of  kind.  Nor  is 
Locke  himself  blind  to  the  contention  I  here  raise.  Such  passages 
as  the  following,  wherein  it  is  declared  that  the  principle  of  uni- 
formity is  involved  in  mathematics  no  less  than  in  knowledge  of 
substances,  help  to  destroy,  by  Locke's  own  confession,  the  very 
essence  of  the  issue  propounded.  "  //  the  perception  that  the  same 
ideas  will  eternally  have  the  same  habitudes  and  relations  be  not  a 
sufficient  ground  of  knowledge,  there  could  be  no  knowledge  of  gen- 


51 

era!  propositions  in  mathematics;  for  no  mathematical  demonstra- 
tion could  be  other  than  particular:  and  when  a  man  has  demon- 
strated any  proposition  concerning  one  triangle  and  circle  his 
knowledge  would  not  reach  beyond  that  particular  diagram/' 7 

Concerning  his  other  claim,  that  of  Inconceivability,  nothing 
more  needs  to  be  said.  An  object  may  be  absolute  for  me  because 
I  cannot  conceive  it  to  be  other  than  it  is.  But  then  at  what  point, 
pray,  is  that  object  in  my  conception  of  it,  or  in  my  inability  to 
conceive  it  otherwise,  unconditioned  ?  And  to  concede  this  point,  is 
to  concede  the  sole  point  at  issue  between  a  relativistic  and  an 
absolute  view  of  an  object.  The  absolute  point  of  view  does  not 
only  require  the  possibility  of  an  unconditioned  and  an  undeter- 
mined object,  but  an  unconditioned  mode  of  perception  or  concep- 
tion as  well.  But,  after  all,  Locke's  interest  centers  itself  primarily 
in  the  determination  of  objects  such  as  they  are.  Let  us  then, 
without  more  ado,  turn  to  his  account  of  modes  as  having  their 
origin  in  Eeason  and  not  in  Experience.  As  this  antithesis  is  a 
false  one,  and  one  that  is  fruitless,  I  shall  not  burden  the  reader 
with  additional  quotations.  Modes,  in  their  proper  character,  as 
has  been  stated,  shall  be  taken  up  for  inquiry  in  future  chapters; 
and  so  with  substances. 


ORIGIN  OF  a  priori  MODES 

Relevant  points,  scattered  throughout  the  Essay  with  endless 
repetition,  may  be  embraced  under  the  following  items:  (a)  that 
these  ideas  are  of  a  real  essence;  (b)  that  they  are  ideas  of 
Reason  and  not  of  Experience;  (c)  "that  wherever  we  can  suppose 
such  a  creature  as  man  is,  endowed  with  such  faculties,  and  thereby 
furnished  with  such  ideas  as  we  have,"  the  same  knowledge  must 
follow;  (d)  "for  the  same  ideas  have  immutably  the  same  rela- 
tions and  habitudes,"  and  (e)  knowledge  is  a  consequence  of 
ideas,  and  not  the  reverse;  hence  (/)  these  ideas  are  primary,  and 
not  the  result  of  knowledge.  And  lastly,  (g)  modes  are  of  the 
Mind's  own  making,  (h)  made  very  arbitrarily.  Consider  these 
items,  and  the  conclusions  to  be  drawn  are,  either  (1)  that  the 
mind  out  of  nothing,  under  necessity  or  at  pleasure,  creates  some- 
thing; or  (2)  that  it  has  native  or  original  ideas  of  its  own,  and 
hence  creates  nothing  but  merely  unfolds  what  is  latent;  or  (3)  that 

7.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  1,  sec.  9. 


52 

it,  within  a  given  experience,  lias  the  faculty  to  create  something 
new,  as  conditioned  within  and  conditioned  without.  Which  con- 
clusion shall  we  accept  ?  The  first  conclusion  is  absurd ;  the  second, 
in  contradiction  with  his  denial  of  innate  ideas;  and  the  third, 
impossible  in  the  light  of  the  antithesis  he  here  sets  up  between 
Reason  and  Experience.  To  conclude,  then,  as  we  did  in  a  previous 
chapter,  that  the  Mind,  according  to  Locke,  has  an  originating 
activity,  seems  to  invite  least  violence  to  all  the  facts  of  the  case. 
This  is  our  positive  conclusion.  It  is  only  when  we  ask  with  Locke, 
as  we  must  in  Book  IY,  what  an  originating  capacity  may  achieve 
where  it  has  no  data,  that  this  positive  conclusion  is  apt  to  get  itself 
overlooked  in  Locke.  Modes  and  abstract  ideas  are  its  products, 
it  is  there  affirmed.  But  if  so,  then  what  constitutes  its  data?  In 
Book  IV,  nothing  else  remains  to  draw  upon  for  such  data  than 
Reason  as  opposed  to  Experience.  But  where  is  Reason,  as  opposed 
to  Experience,  to  get  that  data?  From  innate  ideas?  Hardly 
would  Locke  admit  this.  But  yet,  what  other  alternative  lies  open  to 
us  for  choice?  As  a  result  of  this  dilemma,  modes  and  abstract 
ideas  expose  themselves  to  the  necessity  of  getting  themselves  looked 
upon  here  as  at  once  data  and  product,  as,  at  once,  One  and  the 
Many. 


SUBSTANCES   AS   DEPENDANT   UPON   EXPERIENCE   DIVORCED   FROM 

REASON 

I  turn  from  a  priori  modes  to  consider  a  posteriori  substances. 
With  substances,  Locke  ceases  to  be  merely  dogmatic. 

Knowledge,  as  we  were  told,  depends  upon  the  fulfilment  of 
two  conditions.  First,  that  we,  "  by  the  mere  contemplation  of  any 
idea,"  can  affirm  another  "  which  is  a  necessary  consequence  of  its 
precise  complex  idea,  but  not  contained  in  it."  8  Or  secondly,  that 
"  connections  and  dependencies "  must  be  "  visible,"  and  that 
where  "  connections  and  dependencies  are  not  thus  discoverable  in 
our  ideas,  we  can  have  but  an  experimental  knowledge  of  them."  It 
presupposes  that  our  account  of  knowledge,  in  respect  to  modes, 
was  positive  in  its  outcome,  whereas  the  account  proved  negative, 
save  for  the  one  positive  conclusion  we  drew  above  in  respect  to  his 
view  of  the  mind  as  originating  and  form-giving.  These  convic- 
tions, however,  furnish  the  setting  of  his  inquiries  concerning  sub- 

8.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  6,  sec.  11. 


53 

stances  in  Book  IV.  I  begin  my  account  with  a  passage  from  the 
text:  "Had  we  such  ideas  of  substances  as  to  know  what  real 
constitutions  produce  these  sensible  qualities  we  find  in  them.,  and 
how  these  qualities  flowed  from  thence,  we  could,  by  the  specific 
ideas  of  their  real  essence  in  our  minds,  more  certainly  find  out 
their  properties  and  discover  what  qualities  they  had  or  had  not, 
than  we  can  now  by  our  senses :  and  to  know  the  properties  of  gold, 
it  would  be  no  more  necessary  that  gold  should  exist  and  that  we 
should  make  experiments  upon  it,  than  it  is  nevessary  for  the 
knowing  of  the  properties  of  a  triangle,  that  a  triangle  should 
exist  in  any  matter,  the  idea  in  our  minds  would  serve  for  one  as 
well  as  the  other.  But  we  are  so  far  from  being  admitted  into  the 
secrets  of  nature,  that  we  scarce  so  much  as  ever  approach  the 
entrance  towards  them."  How  monotonous  this  strain  is  in  Locke, 
the  projection  of  the  a  priori  ideal  in  respect  to  substances  and  its 
rejection,  must  be  perfectly  familiar.  Yet  substances  as  of  this  or 
that  collection  of  simple  ideas  do  exist :  How  then  do  we  come  by 
them  ? 


(a)    THE  DISPARATE  AND  DISCRETE  CHARACTER  OF  SUBSTANCES 

"  The  simple  ideas  whereof  our  complex  ideas  of  substances 
are  made  up  are  such  as  carry  with  them,  in  their  own  nature,  no 
visible  necessary  connection  or  inconsistency  with  any  other  simple 
ideas,  whose  co-existence  with  them  we  would  inform  ourselves 
about.  .  .  .  Besides  our  ignorance  of  the  primary  qualities  on  which 
depend  all  their  secondary  qualities,  there  is  yet  another  and 
more  incurable  part  of  ignorance,  .  .  .  and  that  is,  that  there 
is  no  discoverable  connection  between  any  secondary  quality  and 
those  primary  qualities  which  it  depends  on.  ...  We  are  so  far 
from  knowing  what  figure,  size,  or  motion  of  parts  produce  a 
yellow  color,  a  sweet  taste,  or  a  sharp  sound,  that  we  cannot 
by  any  means  conceive  how  any  size,  figure,  or  motion  of  any  par- 
ticles, can  possibly  produce  in  us  the  ideas  of  any  color,  taste  or 
sound  whatsoever;  there  is  no  conceivable  connection  between  the 
one  and  the  other.  .  .  .  How  any  thought  should  produce  a  motion 
in  body  is  as  remote  from  the  nature  of  our  ideas,  as  how  any  body 
should  produce  any  thought  in  the  mind.  ...  In  vain,  therefore, 
shall  we  endeavor  to  discover  by  our  ideas  (the  only  true  way  of 
certain  and  universal  knowledge)  what  other  ideas  are  to  be  found 
constantly  joined  with  that  of  our  complex  idea  of  any  substance. 


54 

...  So,  that,  let  our  complex  idea  of  any  species  of  substance  be 
what  it  will,  we  can  hardly,  from  the  simple  ideas  contained  in  it, 
evidently  determine  the  necessary  co-existence  of  any  other  quality 
whatsoever.  Our  knowledge  in  all  these  inquiries  reaches  very 
little  further  than  our  experience.  .  .  .  That  it  is  so,  if  experience 
did  not  convince  us,  the  consideration  of  the  things  themselves 
would  never  be  able  in  the  least  to  discover  to  us."  9  But  with  ideas 
of  substances  lacking  an  inherent  constitution,  and  also  lacking 
"  discoverable  connections  "  between  them  or  their  parts,  our  con- 
clusion is : 


(6)  IDE  AS    OF    SUBSTAXCES    ARBITRARY    PRODUCTS    AXD    INADEQUATE 

e<  Distinct  ideas  of  the  several  sorts  of  bodies  that  fall  under 
the  examination  of  our  senses  perhaps  we  may  have:  but  adequate 
ideas,  I  suspect,  we  have  not  of  any  one  amongst  them.  .  .  .  Hence 
no  science  of  bodies."  10  They  are  inadequate,  no  matter  what 
specific  determination  we  fix  upon,  because  we  do  not  know,  in 
virtue  of  an  object's  possible  relations,  what  qualities  properly  be- 
long to  it  and  which  do  not.  "  N"o  one  who  hath  considered  the 
properties  of  bodies  in  general,  or  of  gold  in  particular,  can  doubt 
that  this  called  gold  has  infinite  other  properties  not  contained 
in  that  complex  idea  "  that  we,  in  any  specific  case,  may  decide 
upon.  "  So  that  if  we  make  our  complex  idea  of  gold  a  body  yel- 
low, fusible,  ductile,  weighty  and  fixed,  we  shall  be  at  the  same 
uncertainty  concerning  solubility  in  aqua  regia,  and  for  this  reason : 
since  we  can  never,  from  the  consideration  of  the  ideas  themselves, 
with  certainty  affirm  or  deny  of  a  body  whose  complex  idea  is  made 
up  of  yellow,  very  weighty,  etc.,  that  it  is  soluble  in  aqua  regia; 
and  so  on  of  the  rest  of  its  qualities."  12 

The  disparate  and  discrete  character,  then,  of  our  ideas,  the 
indefinite  and  inexhaustible  number  of  them  that  may,  upon  equal 
ground,  come  to  form  a  part  of  any  specific  determination  of  sub- 
stances, and  the  flux  thus  of  necessity  projected  into  our  sub- 
stances, and  his  assumption  that  such  is  not  the  case  with  modes, 
constitute  the  ground  upon  which  Locke  forces  the  sharp  antithesis 
between  modes  and  substances,  or  "  abstract  ideas  and  their  rela- 

9.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  3. 

10.  Ibid.,  sec.  26. 

11.  Bk.  II,  ch.  31,  sec.  10. 

12.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  6,  sec.  9. 


55 

tions "  and  "  matters-of-fact."  Hence,  instead  of  instructive  a 
priori  judgments  being  possible  in  respect  to  substances,  he  forces 
the  contrast  or  antithesis  to  a  point  that  make  substances  seem  in 
Book  IV  as  little  else  than  a  highly  and  equally  capricious  fluctua- 
tion of  parts.  If  only  "  we  had  such  ideas  of  substances  as  to  know 
what  real  constitution  produce  those  sensible  qualities  we  find  in 
them/' 1S  then  all  would  be  well,  so  Locke  keeps  repeating,  and 
certainty,  adequacy  and  universality  in  respect  to  substance  attain- 
able. But  substances  have  no  such  central  core  of  reality,  and, 
then,  he  concludes,  that  they  have  no  adequacy,  no  fixity,  no  truth, 
or  reality  at  all.  NOT  can  the  substitution  of  judgments  of  proba- 
bility for  this  affirmed  lack  of  proper  knowledge  alter  or  improve 
the  situation  any.  If  substances  are  of  a  pure,  unregulated  flux 
in  the  one  case,  they  continue  pure,  unregulated  flux  in  the  other. 
And  the  question  now  is,  not  how  would  we,  but  how  does  Locke 
himself  handle  this  situation?  This  is  the  subject  proper  of 
Book  III  and  of  a  later  chapter. 

Suppose  we  grant  Locke  that  no  abstract  consideration  of  an 
object  can  yield  an  adequate  one, — for  such  is  the  mode  of  his 
approach  and  such  the  conclusion  here  drawn.  Does  it  neces- 
sarily follow  that  an  abstract  consideration  and  determination  of 
an  object  is  the  only  proper  one,  or  that  adequacy  of  an  object 
implies  a  theoretical  exhaustiveness  of  its  infinite  possible  rela- 
tions? We  get  two  distinct  resolutions  of  this  matter  from  Locke 
in  Book  IV,  one  that  is  sceptical  in  its  outcome  and  the  other  that 
is  positive  and  relativistic.  I  shall  consider  the  sceptical  issue 
first. 


THE   PRIMACY   OF    CONDUCT 

He  writes :  "  The  way  of  getting  and  improving  our  knowl- 
edge in  substances  only  by  experience  and  history,  which  is  all 
that  the  weakness  of  our  faculties  .  .  .  can  attain  to,  makes  me 
suspect  that  natural  philosophy  is  not  capable  of  being  made  a 
science  .  .  .  from  whence  it  is  obvious  to  conclude  .  .  .  that 
morality  is  the  proper  science  and  business  of  mankind  in  gen- 
eral." 14  Namely,  in  the  defeat  of  theory  or  science  turn  to  con- 
duct for  truth  and  reality.  This  demands  a  word. 

13.  Ibid.,  sec.  10. 

14.  Ibid.,  ch.  12,  sees.  10-11. 


56 

In  this  deference,  or  better,  abdication  of  knowledge  to  con- 
duct, we  have  a  lurking  fallacy.  When  we  say  knowledge  must 
subordinate  itself  to  conduct,  the  assertion  has  a  certain  perti- 
nency when  a  needful  corrective  of  a  one-sided,  opposite  tendency; 
but  beyond  that  it  has  no  whit  more  pertinency  than  to  say  that 
conduct  must  subordinate  itself  to  knowledge.  If  the  principle  of 
relativity,  erroneously  construed  or  applied,  compasses  the  bank- 
ruptcy of  knowledge  in  theory,  we  cannot  thereafter  logically  ignore 
this  defeat  of  knowledge  and  make  it  do  service  in  a  sphere,  sup- 
posedly different,  as  if  conduct  itself  were  not  disrupted  as  well  as 
the  other  objects.  If  its  supposed  validity  (that  of  the  principle) 
was  the  means  whereby  we  proved  knowledge  a  failure,  then  knowl- 
edge does  not  cease  being  a  failure,  and  as  a  failure,  totally  useless, 
when  made  to  minister  to  conduct,  even  when  granted  that  con- 
duct itself  remained  undisrupted  (as  if  the  principle  of  relativity 
did  not  apply  to  conduct  as  to  all  objects  in  general).  Besides,  to 
speak  of  conduct  in  general  is  to  speak  of  an  abstraction  as  mytho- 
logical as  the  abstraction  involved  in  the  notion  "  matter."  For  con- 
duct, if  it  exists,  exists  in  "  sorts/'  as  Locke  would  say,  and  how  get 
the  "  sorts "  of  conduct  denned,  apart  from  knowledge,  or  apart 
from  the  abstract  idea,  as  he  would  state  it,  which  constitutes  the 
essence  of  each  sort,  if  knowledge  has  previously  been  declared  a 
failure  ?  It  is  not  logical  to  blow  hot  and  cold  with  the  same  prin- 
ciple. Knowledge,  if  not  the  pretended  failure,  may  truly  subserve 
conduct;  but  conduct  no  less  truly  does  subserve  knowledge,  when 
it  is  conduct,  rather  than  some  other  object,  that  demands  a  deter- 
mination, and  without  a  specific  determination  (again  to  speak  in 
Locke's  own  language)  "  particular  beings,  considered  barely  in 
themselves,  may  at  once  be  everything  or  nothing.'' 15  Besides,  the 
principle  of  relativity  disclaims  the  possibility  of  any  absolute  not 
limited  and  restricted.  Otherwise  accepted,  it  is  a  matter  of  bare 
faith  and  a  matter  of  blind  volition,  but  not  a  matter  of  knowl- 
edge. For  how  could  it  be  a  "  matter  of  knowledge  "  when  our  very 
principle  of  knowledge  declares  that  there  can  be  no  absolute  with- 
out limitation  and  restriction,  and  yet  conduct  would  seem  to  set 
itself  up  as  an  Absolute  without  limitations  and  restrictions? 
Then  we  might  further  ask :  Does  it  belong  to  the  class  substances 
or  mixed  modes  ?  To  one  of  them  or  to  simple  ideas  it  must  belong,- 
if  reality  had  thus  been  exhaustively  outlined  by  him.  And  so, 
instead  of  having  conduct  in  reserve  as  a  place  of  safe  retreat, 

15.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6;  sec.  5. 


57 

when  the  world,  otherwise  reared  by  knowledge,  collapses,  he  really 
has  nothing  in  reserve  but  a  bare,  empty  abstraction,  just  as  bare 
and  empty  as  the  notion  "  matter,"  for  example.  Such,  to  my  mind, 
is  the  fallacy;  the  truth  contained  in  the  conduct-reference  this: 
that  the  ends,  aims  and  values  of  life,  ^is  revealed  in  conduct, 
cannot  be  prevented  from  reflecting  themselves  in  the  form,  char- 
acter, and  structure  of  things  as  of  this  or  that  sort;  that  the 
reality  that  thus  reflects  itself  in  the  various  sorts  is  no  less  cognitive 
in  quality  than  sense-perceptions;  and,  according  to  the  principle 
of  relativity,  may  be  either  more  or  less  real  than  sense-perceptions, 
as  being  a  thing,  in  large  measure,  as  dependent  upon  other  things 
as  other  things  in  turn  are  dependent  upon  it.  I  shall  return  to 
this  particular  issue  in  subsequent  chapters. 

This  general  conclusion  is  confirmed  in  Locke's  positive  solu- 
tion of  the  above-mentioned  theoretical  defeat.  The  note  is  a  recur- 
rent one  and  a  brief  citation  will  suffice  for  a  statement  of  the 
position.  "  Our  faculties  being  suited,  not  to  the  full  extent  of 
being,  nor  to  a  perfect,  clear,  comprehensive  knowledge  of  things 
free  from  all  doubt  and  scruple;  but  to  the  preservation  of  us,  in 
whom  they  are,  and  accommodated  to  the  use  of  life,  they  serve  to 
our  purpose  well  enough,  if  they  will  but  give  us  certain  notice  of 
those  things  which  are  convenient  or  inconvenient  to  us.  .  .  . 
So  that  this  evidence  is  as  great  as  we  can  desire,  being  as  certain 
to  us  as  our  pleasure  or  pain,  i.e.,  happiness  or  misery;  beyond 
which  we  have  no  concernment  either  of  knowing  or  being."  16  In 
other  words,  instead  of  defining  an  object's  truth,  reality,  and 
adequacy  or  inadequacy  in  abstraction  and  in  its  isolation,  he  seeks 
here  to  define  them  in  terms  of  a  purpose,  in  terms  of  a  limit  or 
condition  which  our  '  needs '  impose.  But  even  in  this  shift  in  his 
position,  it  may  be  held,  he  has  not  gained  anything,  except  to 
extend  his  principle  of  relativity  to  include  a  new  source  of  change 
or  determination:  a  further  determination  of  objects  in  reference 
to  our  needs,  constitution,  or  ends.  Instead  of  less  flux,  then,  we 
ought  really  to  expect  more.  And,  if  not,  may  we  ask  why?  It 
does  not  introduce  more  flux,  because  he  assumes  a  certain  fixity 
in  such  needs,  constitution,  or  ends.  But  by  what  right  has  he  to 
assume  a  fixity  in  these  objects  and  fail  to  assume  a  higher  degree 
of  fixity  than  he  does  in  objects  in  general?  And  suppose  we 
answer,  by  reference  to  experience,  that  a  fixity  is  here  recognized, 
not  recognized  in  respect  to  objects  in  general ;  that  my  own  needs, 

16.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  11,  sec.  8;    ch.  12,  sec.  11;   Bk.  II,  eh.  23,  sees.  12-13. 


58 

constitution,,  and  ends  fluctuate  less  than  such  an  object  as  a  stone, 
let  us  say;  and  then  we  may  ask  further:  is  this  true?  And  if 
not  true,  we  have  gained  one*  vast  admission  in  respect  to  sub- 
stances :  the  collections  of  ideas,  constituting  this  or  that  substance, 
do  not  share  equally  in*  their  degree  of  stability  or  flux,  and  this 
Locke  himself  tacitly  admits  in  his  account  of  primary  and  sec- 
ondary ideas  and  explicitly  admits  or  presents  in  his  empirical  and 
constructive  relativity.  Moreover,  Locke  does  not  deny  that  things 
"  proceed  regularly  "  17  and  that  "  we  may  conclude  do  act  by  a  law 
set  them."  18  He  merely  insists  upon  the  fact,  that,  even  if  they 
act  by  a  law  set  them,  it  is  "  a  law  that  we  know  not."  19  It  is  thus 
the  sensuous  unknowability  and  not  the  non-existence  of  a  law  or 
order  or  union  of  parts  that  Locke  insists  upon. 

The  reality,  truth,  adequacy,  and  certainty  of  simple  ideas  in 
general,  he  defines  in  the  same  way.  They  are  real,  etc.,  for  the 
reason,  as  he  repeats  over  and  over  again,  "  that  they  represent 
to  us  things  under  those  appearances  which  they  are  fitted  to  pro- 
duce in  us,  whereby  we  are  enabled  to  distinguish  the  sorts  of  par- 
ticular substances,  to  discern  the  state  they  are  in,  and  so  to  take 
them  for  our  necessities,  and  apply  them  to  our  uses."  :  Objects 
are  thus  regarded  as  partaking  of  certainty  and  adequacy  when  we 
hold  them  fixed  in  a  certain  definite  and  restricted  context,  of 
whicli  context  it  forms  an  integral  part.  Instead  of  defining  an 
object's  adequacy  or  inadequacy  in  abstraction,  wherein  however 
we  are  really  at  pains  to  seek  its  definition  in  an  unlimited  and 
unbounded  context,  Locke  here  again  seeks  to  establish  the  validity 
of  defining  it,  according  to  needs,  in  a  limited  and  specific  context, 
and  the  context  itself  of  a  contracted  or  expanded  boundary,  as  the 
case  may  be  or  demand.  The  a  priori  element  which  he  felt  must 
exist,  and  exist  at  the  heart  of  things  in  order  to  set  their 
limits  and  bounds  and  fixity,  we  now  find,  by  this  other  view  of 
his,  to  center  in  certain  uniformities  in  the  connection  of  facts, 
although  such  facts  are  disparate  in  character  and  their  interde- 
pendence an  appearance  only,  and  to  depend  upon  needs,  interests, 
or  aims.  We  are  now  ready  to  turn  to  Locke's  doctrines  in  their 
most  perfect  form  as  deliberately  elaborated  by  him. 

17.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  3,  sec.  29. 

18.  Ibid. 

19.  Ibid. 

20.  Ibid.,  ch.  4,  sec.  4. 


IV 

CONSTRUCTIVE  RELATIVITY  IN  LOCKE 
CHAPTER  IX 

DOCTRINE  OF  SORTS  I  MIXED  MODES  AND  SUBSTAXCKs 

BY  sorts,  Locke  understands  things  as  of  this  or  that  specific 
determination  or  kind,  as  horse,  stone,  charity,  murder.  How  do 
we  come  by  them  ? 

In  the  first  place,  Locke  makes  both  substances  and  modes  de- 
pendent upon  simple  ideas  or  the  so-called  nominal  essence.  "  The 
supposition  of  a  real  essence  that  cannot  be  known, "  such  is  his 
position,  "  is  so  wholly  useless  and  unserviceable  to  any  part  of  our 
knowledge,  that  that  alone  were  sufficient  to  make  us  lay  it  by,  and 
content  ourselves  with  such  essences  of  the  sorts  or  species  of 
things  [namely,  the  nominal]  as  come  within  the  reach  of  our 
knowledge."  l 

Kext,  they  are  held  to  agree  in  the  fact  "  that  sorts,  as  distin- 
guished and  denominated  by  us,  neither  are  nor  can  be  anything 
but  those  precise  abstract  ideas  we  have  in  our  minds."  :  Hence 
his  conclusion  in  respect  to  both :  "  Each  distinct  abstract  idea  is 
a  distinct  Essence.  .  .  .  Thus  a  circle  is  as  essentially  different 
from  an  oval  as  a  sheep  from  a  goat;  and  rain  is  as  essentially 
different  from  snow  as  water  from  earth.  .  .  .  Thus  any  two 
abstract  ideas,  that  in  any  part  vary  one  from  another,  with  two 
distinct  names  annexed  to  them,  constitute  two  distinct  sorts,  as 
essentially  different  as  any  two  of  the  most  remote  or  opposite  in  the 
world."  3' 

1.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  3,  sec.   17. 

2.  Ibid.,  sec.   13. 

3.  Ibid.,  sec.  14. 

59 


60 

Beyond  these  points  of  agreement,  however,  modes  and  sub- 
stances begin  to  get  themselves  more  or  less  sharply  distinguished. 
Let  me  enumerate  these  differences  before  turning  to  modes  and 
substances  for  separate  and  enlarged  discussion. 

Modes,  in  theory,  are  made  dependent  (a)  solely  upon  simple 
ideas  and  ( & )  upon  "  the  free  choice  of  the  mind,"  giving  a  union 
or  connection  to  a  certain  number  of  these  ideas.  Substances,  on 
the  other  hand,  are  not  solely  dependent  upon  simple  ideas,  but 
upon  their  constant  and  inseparable  union  in  Nature  as  well.  Sub- 
stances "  carry  with  them  the  supposition  of  some  real  being,  from 
which  its  complex  ideas  are  taken  and  to  which  they  are  conform- 
able. But,  in  its  complex  ideas  of  mixed  modes,  the  mind  takes  a 
liberty  not  to  follow  the  existence  of  things  exactly."  4 

The  two  are  said  to  be  very  different  in  another  essential :  modes 
dealing  with  intangible  as  well  as  tangible  elements;  whereas  sub- 
stances are  thought  to  deal  with  the  tangible  only.  "  And  hence 
I  think  it  is  that  these  mixed  modes  are  called  notions,  as  if  they 
had  their  original  and  constant  existence  more  in  the  thought  of 
men,  than  in  the  reality  of  things ;  and  to  form  such  ideas,  it  sufficed 
that  the  mind  puts  the  parts  of  them  together,  and  that  they  were 
consistent  in  the  understanding,  without  considering  whether  they 
had  any  real  being ;  though  I  do  not  deny  but  several  of  them  might 
be  taken  from  observation,  and  the  existence  of  several  simple  ideas 
so  combined."  5  From  this  follows  the  more  peculiar  dependence 
of  modes  upon  words,  as  "  the  sensible  signs  of  his  ideas  who  uses 
them."  6 


I.    MIXED   MODES 

By  mixed  modes,  then,  Locke  understands  such  "  complex  ideas 
as  we  mark  by  the  names  obligation,  drunkenness,  a  lie,  etc.  .  .  . 
being  fleeting  and  transient  combinations  of  simple  ideas,  which 
have  but  a  short  existence  anywhere  but  in  the  minds  of  men."  7 
How  do  we  come  by  them?  Inherently  many,  how  do  they  come 
by  their  unity  ?  "  Every  mixed  mode,  consisting  of  many  distinct 
simple  ideas,  it  seems  reasonable  to  inquire,  '  whence  it  has  its 
unity,  and  how  such  a  precise  multitude  comes  to  make  but  one 

4.  Ibid.,  ch.  5,  sec.  3. 

5.  Bk.   II,  ch.   22,  sec.   2. 

6.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  2,  sec.  2. 

7.  Bk.  II,  ch.  22,  sees.  1  and  8. 


61 

idea/   since  that  combination  does   not  always  exist  together  in 
nature."  8 

Our  subject  breaks  up  into  three  parts: 

1.  Their   independence  of   Mature   and   dependence  upon  the 
mind  and  its  simple  ideas. 

2.  Their  dependence  upon  Xature. 

3.  Every   distinct  abstract  idea  is  a  distinct  essence  or  sort. 
Division  three  constitutes  a  far  more  vital  issue  in  connection 

with  substances.     Special  consideration  of  this  matter,  then,  were 
best  reserved  for  such  place. 


1.    TIIELJJ    J.\l)El'i:Nl)KNCK    OF    XATUKi:    AXI)    DKL'MXDKNCE    UPOX    THE 
MIXD  AXD  ITS  SIMPLE  IDKAs 

••  Nobody  can  doubt,"  he  writes  "that  these  ideas  of  mixed 
modes  are  made  by  a  voluntary  collection  of  ideas,  put  together  in 
the  mind,  independent  from  any  original  patterns  in  nature.  .  .  . 
For  what  greater  connection  in  nature  has  the  idea  of  a  man  than 
the  idea  of  a  sheep  with  killing,  that  this  is  made  a  particular 
species  of  action,  signified  by  the  word  murder,  and  the  other  not. 
.  .  .  It  is  evident  then,  that  the  mind  by  its  free  choice  gives  a 
connection  to  a  certain  number  of  ideas,  which  in  nature  have  no 
more  union  with  one  another  than  others  that  it  leaves  out;  .  .  . 
whereof  the  intranslatable  words  of  divers  languages  are  a  proof, 
which  could  not  have  happened,  if  these  species  were  the  steady 
workmanship  of  nature,  and  not  collections  made  by  the  mind." 
Furthermore,  mixed  modes  "  do  often  unite  into  one  abstract  idea 
things  that,  in  their  nature,  have  no  coherence;  and  so  under  one 
term  bundle  together  a  great  variety  of  compounded  and  decom- 
pounded ideas  .  .  .  often  involving  actions  that  required  time 
to  their  performance,  and  so  could  never  all  exist  together.  .  .  . 
Thus  the  name  of  procession,  what  a  great  mixture  of  independent 
ideas  of  persons,  habits,  tapers,  orders,  motions,  sound,  does  it 
contain  in  that  complex  one,  which  the  mind  of  man  has  arbitrarily 
put  together."  Or  again,  "  when  we  speak  of  justice  or  ingratitude, 
we  frame  to  ourselves  no  imagination  of  anything  existing,  which 
we  would  conceive;  but  our  thoughts  terminate  in  the  abstract 
ideas  of  those  virtues,  and  look  not  further,  as  they  do  when  we 
speak  of  a  horse  or  iron,  whose  specific  ideas  we  consider,  not  as 

8.  Bk.  II,  ch.  22,  sec.  4. 


62 

barely  in  the  mind,  but  as  in  things  themselves,  which  afford  the 
original  patterns  of  those  ideas.  For  the  originals  of  mixed 
modes  then,,  we  look  no  further  than  the  mind,  which  also  shows 
them  to  be  the  workmanship  of  the  Understanding.9  Turn  where 
we  will  in  his  account  of  mixed  modes,  this  line  of  argument  will 
be  found  continually  repeating  itself. 

That  this  description  of  them  contains  a  tremendous  element 
of  truth  cannot  be  denied.  The  mind  certainly  has  the  capacity 
of  holding  parts  together  and  keeping  them  fixed  and  distinct  so 
that  "  any  two  abstract  ideas,  that  in  any  part  vary  one  from 
another  .  .  .  constitute  two  distinct  sorts,  as  essentially  different 
as  any  two  of  the  most  remote  and  opposite  in  the  world."  10 
Furthermore,  we  cannot  deny  the  radical  character  of  the  Many 
in  such  ideas  as  those  cited;  namely,  the  notion  of  a  procession. 
Nor  can  we  deny  the  arbitrary  character  in  their  determination, 
so  much  insisted  upon  by  him ;  not  any  more  than  we  can  deny  the 
presence  of  an  intangible  element:  "what  the  word  murder  or 
sacrilege,  etc.,  signifies  can  never  be  known  from  things  themselves : 
there  be  many  of  the  parts  of  those  complex  ideas  which  are  not 
visible  in  the  action  itself ;  the  intention  of  the  mind  or  the  relation 
of  holy  things,  which  make  a  part  of  murder  or  sacrilege,  have  no 
necessary  connection  with  the  outward  and  visible  action  of  him 
that  commits  either."  1X  What  we  may  deny,  is  the  range  he 
ascribes  to  "  the  mind  in  its  liberty  not  to  follow  the  existence  of 
things  exactly,"  as  if  it  were  in  no  sense  dependent  at  all.  The 
corrective  of  this  view  exists  in  his  pages?  This  shall  constitute 
the  subject-matter  of  our  next  division : 


2.   DEPENDENCE   UPON   NATURE 

I  stated  above  that,  in  theory,  Locke  distinguishes  modes  from 
substances  in  the  quality  that  substances  are  dependent  upon 
Nature  for  their  pattern,  whereas  modes  are  not  thus  dependent; 
but  dependent  solely  upon  its  simple  ideas  and  "  the  free  choice 
of  the  mind,  pursuing  its  own  ends."  12  But  instead  of  the  affirmed 
dependence  upon  simple  ideas  only,  we  find  them  dependent  at 
least  in  part,  "upon  experience  and  observation  of  things  tlicni- 

9.  See  Bk.  II,  ch.  22 ;    Bk.  Ill,  ch.  5. 

10.  Bk.   Ill,   ch.   3,   sec.    14. 

11.  Ibid.,  ch.  9,  sec.  7. 

12.  Ibid.,  ch.  5,  sec.  6. 


63 

selves;  .  .  .  for  their  immediate  ingredients  are  also  complex  ideas,, 
although  all  our  complex  ideas  are  ultimately  resolvable  into  simple 
ideas."  13  Or  again,  "  action  being  the  great  business  of  mankind, 
and  the  whole  matter  about  which  laws  are  conversant,  it  is  no 
wonder  [that  mixed  modes  should  be  made  so  largely  out  of  them] . 
.  .  .  Nor  could  any  communication  be  well  had  amongst  men  with- 
out such  complex  ideas,  with  names  to  them:  and  therefore  men 
have  settled  names,  and  supposed  ideas  in  their  minds,  of  modes 
of  action  distinguishable  by  their  causes,  means,  objects,  instru- 
ments, time,  place,  and  other  circumstances,  and  also  of  their 
powers  fitted  for  those  actions,"  14  which  amounts  to  an  admission 
that  modes  are  shaped  and  generated  in  concrete  and  complex  sit- 
uations ;  just  as  his  notion  of  "  the  mind,  pursuing  its  own  ends," 
gets  its  ends  defined  as  "  the  end  of  language,"  or  as  ends  generated 
"  in  the  ordinary  occurrence  of  affairs.  So  that,  if  they  join  to 
the  idea  of  killing  the  idea  of  father  or  mother,  and  so  make  a  dis- 
tinct species  from  killing  a  man's  son  or  neighbor,  it  is  because  of 
the  different  heinousness  of  the  crime,  and  the  distinct  punishment 
due  to  the  murdering  of  a  man's  father  or  mother,  different  from 
what  ought  to  be  inflicted  on  the  murder  of  a  son  or  neighbor ;  .  .  . 
which  plainly  shows,  whereof  the  intranslatable  words  of  divers 
languages  are  a  proof,  that  those  of  one  country,  by  their  customs- 
and  manners  of  life,  have  found  occasion  to  make  several  complex 
ideas,  and  given  names  to  them  which  others  never  collected  into 
specific  ideas."  15  It  is  when  we  consider  modes  as  thus  dependent,, 
that  they  get  to  distinguish  themselves  from  substances  in  aspects 
only — in  the  incorporation  of  a  value-elenient :  and,  in  like  manner, 
get  themselves  closely  identified  with  his  "  ideas  of  Eelation."  It  is 
significant  that  in  Book  III  relations  and  modes  are  dealt  with 
as  if  they  presented  no  differences. 

Without  needlessly  dragging  out  this  account,  we  may  formu- 
late the  following  conclusions  as  emerging  from  his  description  of 
modes:  (1)  They  are  inherently  many  and  get  their  unity  in  an 
abstract  idea;  (2)  that  Ends,  as  manifesting  themselves  in  com- 
plex situations,  co-operate  in  determining  their  origin  and  specific 
character;  (3)  that  value  and  meaning  enter  them  as  inseparable 
elements  or  ingredients;  (4)  they  are  constructs  and  not  copies, 
and,  such  as  they  are,  inherently  relative. 

13.  Bk.  II,  ch.  22,  sec.  9.     Italics  are  mine. 

14.  Ibid.,  sec.  10. 

15.  Ibid.,  sees.  7-8. 


II.    SUBSTANCES 

If  it  be  true,  as  I  think  we  have  every  reason  to  maintain,  that 
Locke,  like  men  in  general,  is  interested  primarily  in  things,  and 
in  their  ground,  foundation,  origin,  or  explanation  only  so  far  as 
they  will  serve  to  account  for  "  those  notions  of  things  we  have/' 
then  his  account  of  substances  at  its  best  (not  to  speak  of  modes 
and  relations),  ought  to  be  the  real  test  of  his  theories,  as  far  as 
Locke's  own  successful  application  of  them  is  concerned,  in  the 
service  of  the  more  proper  understanding  of  which  such  theories 
were  called  into  existence.  Now  in  regard  to  modes,  whether  simple 
or  mixed,  he  never  gets  lost  as  to  his  real  issue ;  whether  or  not  we 
agree  with  his  account  "whereby  the  understanding  comes  by 
them,"  is  quite  another  matter.  In  regard  to  substances,  the  issue 
is  not  fully  and  frankly  met  until  we  come  to  Book  III.  Here 
the  issue,  at  length,  gets  itself  clearly  stated :  "  Why  do  we  say 
this  is  a  horse,  and  that  a  mule;  this  is  an  animal,  that  an  herb? 
How  comes  any  particular  thing  to  be  of  this  or  that  sort  ?  "  16 
His  answer  is  that  they  are  constructs  and  not  copies ;  achievements 
attained  through  trials,  experimentation,  and  comparisons,  in  a 
world  where  resemblances  among  things,  as  well  as  "  regular  and 
constant  union  "  among  ideas,  is  accepted  by  him  as  a  fact,  and  our 
sole  knowable  reality  that  designated  by  him  as  nominal.  How  can 
our  objects  be  copies,  when  objects  reveal  different  qualities  and 
properties  in  different  situations,  and  where  "  there  is  not  so  com- 
plete and  perfect  a  part  that  we  know  of  Nature,  which  does  not  owe 
the  being  it  has,  and  the  excellencies  of  it,  to  its  neighbors: 
and  that  we  must  not  confine  our  thoughts  within  the  surface  of  any 
body,  but  look  a  great  deal  further,  to  comprehend  perfectly  those 
qualities  that  are  in  it."  17  Hence  his  conclusion  that  our  ideas  or 
conceptions,  not  "  only'  depend  upon  the  mind  of  man  variously 
collecting  "  or  elaborating  them,  but,  even  at  their  best,  are  "  seldom 
adequate  to  the  internal  nature  of  the  things  they  are  taken  from."  18 

The  mind,  "  in  making  its  complex  ideas  of  substances,  never 
puts  any  together  that  do  not  really  or  are  not  supposed  to  co-exist; 
and  so  it  truly  borrows  that  union  from  nature.  .  .  .  Nobody  joins 
the  voice  of  a  sheep  with  the  shape  of  a  horse,  nor  the  color  of  lead 
with  the  weight  and  fixedness  of  gold,  to  be  the  complex  ideas  of 

16.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sec.  7. 

17.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  6,  sees.  11-12;   Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sec.  32. 

18.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sec.  37. 


65 

any  real  substances;  unless  he  has  a  mind  to  fill  his  head  with 
chimeras."  19  But  if  this  be  true,  as  already  intimated,  substances 
are  not  only  dependent  upon  simple  ideas  but  upon  "  their  constant 
and  inseparable  union  in  nature  as  well."  But  we  may  ask  again, 
as  we  did  above:  what  extension  in  the  meaning  of  the  nominal 
essence,  or  the  simple  idea  doctrine,  is  herein  presumed?  The 
simple  ideas  of  taste,  color,  etc.,  cannot  be  our  sole  type  of  a  real 
perception,  if  sequence  or  co-existence  is  also  a  type  of  reality,  and 
yet  no  mere  taste,  color,  etc.  For  to  deny  this  fact  a  reality  of  some 
kind,  is  to  deny  the  reality  of  every  complex  idea  in  so  far  as  it  is 
complex.  In  the  meantime,  the  reality  of  a  distinction  between  a 
horse  and  a  mule,  an  animal  and  an  herb  persists,  as  well  as  his 
question :  how  does  any  particular  thing  come  to  be  of  this  or  that 
sort?  Xow  in  Book  III,  the  complex  idea  never  has  its  reality 
questioned,  save  in  the  one  point :  "  Does  it  truly  borrow  its  union 
from  nature  ?  "  If  it  does,  it  may  grow  ever  more  and  more  com- 
plex, and,  in  so  doing,  makes  itself  ever  more  perfect  and  adequate. 
Substances,  as  sorts,  according  to  Locke,  are  gotten  in  no  other  way. 
The  sole  issue  that  he  here  considers  pertains  to  the  fact  whether 
our  sort- view  of  an  object  does  or  does  not  limit  and  define  its 
whole  "  measure  and  boundary."  That  the  sort- view  exhausts  our 
total  view  of  objects,  is  his  firm  contention — a  contention  directly 
at  variance  with  his  cruder  dogmatism  that  fact  and  meaning  stand 
in  absolute  divorce.  But  more  of  this  a  little  further  on !  For  the 
present,  let  us  continue  to  direct  our  attention  more  particularly  to 
their  genesis  or  formation.  On  this  point  he  writes  to  the  following 
effect :  "  In  the  substance  of  gold,  one  man  satisfies  himself  with 
color  and  weight,  yet  another  thinks  solubility  in  aqua  regia  as 
necessary  to  be  joined  with  that  color  in  his  idea  of  gold,  as  any 
one  does  its  fusibility;  solubility  in  aqua  regia  being  a  quality 
as  constantly  joined  with  its  color  and  weight  as  fusibility  or  any 
other  [of  its  infinite  possible  number].  Who  of  all  these  has 
established  the  right  signification  of  the  word,  gold  ?  or  who  shall  be 
judge  to  determine?  Each  has  his  standard  in  nature,  which  he 
appeals  to,  and  with  reason  thinks  he  has  the  same  right  to  put  into 
his  complex  idea  signified  by  the  word  gold, , those  qualities,  which, 
upon  trial,  he  has  found  united;  as  another  who  has  not  so  well 
examined  has  to  leave  them  out;  or  a  third  who  has  made  other 
trials,  has  to  put  in  others.  .  .  .  From  hence  it  will  unavoidably 
follow  that  the  complex  ideas  of  substances  [and  the  same  fact  holds 
with  modes]  will  be  very  various,  and  so  the  signification  of  those 

19.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sees.  28-29. 


66 

names  very  uncertain.."  20  Or  again :  "  If  we  will  examine  it,  we 
shall  not  find  the  nominal  essence  of  any  one  species  of  substances 
in  all  men  the  same :  no,  not  of  that  which  of  all  others  we  are  the 
most  intimately  acquainted  with.  Xor  could  it  possibly  be,  that  the 
abstract  idea,  to  which  the  name  man  is  given,  should  be  different 
in  several  men,  if  it  were  of  nature's  making  "  21 ;  that  is,  if  it  were 
a  copy,  and  not  a  construct^  "  Men  generally  content  themselves 
with  some  few  sensible  obvious  qualities;  and  often,  if  not  always, 
leave  out  others  as  material  and  as  firmly  united  as  those  that  they 
take."  22  It  only  remained  necessary  for  him  to  have  correlated 
with  substances,  at  this  point,  his  modes,  relations,  and  his 
"  practical "  motive  or  the  Self,  to  have  given  his  philosophy  all  the 
unity  we  could  have  desired  of  it;  for  by  the  incorporation  of  the 
Self,  as  he  does  in  his  scattered  and  unsystematic  manner,  our 
notion  of  "  nature  "  also  would  have  been  widened,  with  its  addi- 
tional standard  of  reference.  His  emphasis  upon  diversity  in  our 
conceptions  of  substances,  constitutes  a  line  of  argument  whereby 
he  seeks  to  establish  that  substances  are  not  copies,  but  constructs ; 
"  not  of  nature's  making,  but  of  man's." 

But  by  the  side  of  this  view  in  Locke,  wherein  our  notion  of 
objects  is  presented  in  the  light  of  constructs,  the  complex  ideas 
thereby  formed  growing  fuller  and  richer  in  content,  Locke  pre- 
sents another  view  of  abstract  or  complex  ideas,  wherein  he  affirms 
that  "  the  more  general  our  ideas  are,  the  more  incomplete  and 
partial  they  are."  As  the  student  of  Locke  commonly  goes  astray 
here,  the  matter  needs  to  be  cleared  up  before  proceeding  with  the 
above  line  of  thought.  The  following  passage  from  Locke,  though 
quoted  at  length,  demands  no  apology :  "  If  the  simple  ideas  that 
make  the  nominal  essence  of  the  lowest  species  or  first  sorting  of 
individuals,  depends  upon  the  mind  of  man  variously  collecting 
them,  it  is  much  more  evident  that  they  do  so  in  the  more  com- 
prehensive classes,  which,  by  the  masters  of  logic,  are  called  genera. 
.  .  .  This  is  done  by  leaving  out  those  qualities  which  are  peculiar 
to  each  sort  and  retaining  a  complex  idea  made  up  of  those  that  are 
common  to  them  all;  .  .  .  whereby  it  is  plain  that  men  follow  not 
exactly  the  patterns  set  them  by  nature  when  they  make  their 
general  ideas  of  substances,  since  there  is  no  body  to  be  found  which 
has  barely  malleableness  and  fusibility  in  it  [as  in  the  case  of  the 
abstract '  general  idea '  metal]  without  other  qualities  as  inseparable 

20.  Ibid.,  ch.  9,  sec.   13. 

21.  Ibid.,   ch.   6,  sec.   26. 

22.  Ibid.,  sec.  29. 


67 

as  those.  But  men,  in  making  their  general  ideas,  seek- 
ing more  the  convenience  of  language  and  quick  dispatch  by 
short  comprehensive  signs,  than  the  true  and  precise  nature  of 
things  as  they  exist,  have,  in  the  framing  their  abstract  (general) 
ideas,  chiefly  pursued  that  end,  which  was  to  be  furnished  with  a 
store  of  general  and  variously  comprehensive  names.  So  that  in 
this  whole  business  of  genera  and  species,  the  genus,  or  more  com- 
prehensive, is  but  a  partial  conception  of  what  is  in  the  species,  and 
the  species  but  a  partial  idea  of  what  is  to  be  found  in  each  individ- 
ual. .  .  .  If  we  would  rightly  consider  what  is  done  in  all  these 
genera  and  species,  or  sorts,  we  should  find  that  there  is  no  new 
thing  made,  but  only  more  or  less  comprehensive  signs.  ...  In  all 
which  we  may  observe  that  the  more  general  term  is  always  the 
name  of  a  less  complex  idea,  and  that  each  genus  is  but  a  partial 
conception  of  the  species  comprehended  under  it.  So  that  if  these 
abstract  general  ideas  be  thought  to  be  complete,"  it  can  only  be  in 
respect  to  the  ends  of  language  which  called  them  forth,  "  and  not 
in  respect  of  anything  existing,  as  made  by  nature."  23  It  is  hard 
to  find  a  more  suggestive  passage  in  Locke.  First,  we  here  have  his 
distinction  between  particular  abstract  ideas  and  general  abstract 
ideas,  or  so-termed  constructs  and  the  commonly  termed  abstract 
ideas ;  the  former  involving  the  mind  in  its  "  compounding  "  char- 
acter, the  latter  involving  it  in  its  more  narrowly  "  abstracting  " 
character.  Secondly,  within  this  difference,  it  is  further  to  be  noted 
that  they  are  alike  in  being  but  partial  and  incomplete  determina- 
tions of  things ;  the  general  abstract  idea  is  a  "  partial  conception  of 
what  is  in  the  species,  and  the  species  but  a  partial  idea  of  what  is  to 
be  found  in  each  individual."  Thirdly,  that  the  general  abstract  idea, 
"  if  thought  to  be  complete  "  can  on]  j  be  so  in  respect  to  a  certain 
end,  just  as  was  found  to  be  the  case  with  modes,  and  as  is  found  to 
be  the  case  with  the  particular  abstract  idea :  "  men  generally  con- 
tent themselves  with  some  few  sensible  obvious  qualities  .  .  .  which 
serve  well  enough  for  gross  and  confused  conceptions,  and  inac- 
curate ways  of  talking  and  thinking;  .  .  .  most  men  wanting  either 
time,  inclination,  or  industry  enough"  to  determine  their  ideas 
more  fully,  or  "  even  to  some  tolerable  degree,  contenting  them- 
selves with  some  few  obvious  and  outward  appearances  of  things, 
thereby  readily  to  distinguish  and  sort  them  for  the  common  affairs 
of  life.241  So  that,  if  maintained,  that  Locke's  notion  of  sorts  is  an 
abstraction,  the  rather  contrary  statement  may  be  offered  as  a 

23.  Ibid.,  sec.  32. 

24.  Ibid.,  sees.  28-29. 


68 

rejoinder :  his  general  abstract  ideas  as  "  partial  conceptions," 
which,  proceed  in  their  formation  "  by  leaving  out  qualities,"  are 
rather  of  the  nature  of  constructs  even  though  more  obviously 
"  inadequate  to  the  internal  nature  of  the  things  they  are  taken 
from." 

As  the  conclusion  here  drawn  will  be  confirmed  by  what  follows, 
I  proceed  with  my  account,  presenting  the  matter  in  his  own 
language  whenever  possible.  "  This,  then,  in  short,  is  the  case,"  he 
writes.  "  Nature  makes  many  particular  things  which  do  agree  one 
with  another  in  many  sensible  qualities,  and  probably  too  in  their 
internal  frame  and  constitution;  but  it  is  not  this  real  essence  that 
distinguishes  them  into  species;  it  is  men,  who,  taking  occasion 
from  the  qualities  they  find  united  in  them,  and  wherein  they 
observe  often  several  individuals  to  agree,  range  them  into  sorts; 
under  which  individuals,  according  to  their  conformity  to  this  or 
that  abstract  idea,  come  to  be  ranked  as  under  ensigns ;  so  that  this 
is  a  man,  that  a  drill."  25  In  other  words,  we  may  here,  as  in  the 
case  of  gold,  follow  the  '  compounding '  process  or  the  '  eliminating  ' 
process;  the  process  making  for  a  fuller  and  richer  complex  idea, 
or  the  process  making  for  a  more  partial  one; — no  single  object, 
for  example,  a  tree,  in  any  single  instance  of  its  actual  existence, 
embodying  all  the  varied  qualities  embraced  in  any  notion  of  a  tree, 
not  any  more  so  than  "  that  particular  parcel  of  matter  which  makes 
the  ring  on  my  finger"  exhausts  all  the  ideas  of  gold  by  complex 
idea  of  gold  stands  for.  Or  gold  may  be  viewed  under  the  more 
'  partial  idea '  the  word  metal  stands  for ;  and  the  same  with  the 
object  tree.  Thus  he  writes :  "  It  is  necessary  for  me  to  be  as  I  am ; 
God  and  nature  has  made  me  so;  but  there  is  nothing  I  have  is 
essential  to  me.  An  accident  or  disease  may  take  away  my  reason 
or  memory,  or  both,  and  an  apoplexy  leave  neither  sense  nor  under- 
standing, no,  nor  life.  Other  creatures  of  my  shape  may  be  made 
with  more  and  better,  or  fewer  and  worse  faculties  than  I  have ;  and 
others  may  have  reason  and  sense  in  a  shape  and  body  very  different 
from  mine.  None  of  these  are  essential  to  the  one,  or  the  other,  or 
to  any  individual  whatever,  till  the  mind  refers  it  to  some  sort  or 
species  of  things ;  and  then  presently,  according  to  the  abstract  idea 
of  that  sort,  something  is  found  essential.  ...  So  that  if  it  be  asked, 
whether  it  be  essential  to  me  or  any  other  particular  corporeal 
being  to  have  reason  ?  I  say,  no ;  no  more  than  it  is  essential  to  this 
white  thing  I  write  on  to  have  words  in  it.  But  if  that  particular 

l\j.  Ibid.,  sees.  35-36. 


69 

is  to  be  counted  of  the  sort  man,  and  to  have  the  name  man 
given  it,  then  reason  is  essential  to  it,  supposing  reason  to  be  a  part 
of  the  complex  idea  the  name  man  stands  for;  as  it  is  essential  to 
this  thing  I  write  on  to  contain  words  if  I  will  give  it  the  name 
treatise,  and  rank  it  under  that  species."  26  That  is  to  say,  the 
mind  in  making  its  complex  ideas  depends  upon  particular  instances 
of  a  common  thing,  in  order  to  ascertain  the  different  qualities 
which  it  ought  to  unite  in  it;  which  operation  may  be  pursued 
under  this  or  that  end,  and  hence  leading  up  to  different  results  in 
the  way  of  a  complex  idea ;  whereupon  these  ideas,  as  thus  variously 
determined,  and,  as  thus  determined,  held  fixed,  get  to  determine 
the  essence  of  that  object's  species  brought  under  conformity  with 
it.  Accordingly,  my  aim  in  one  case  may  be  the  knowledge  of  some- 
thing in  its  fullest  possible  particular  character,  as  in  the  case  of 
gold  or  man,  in  the  course  of  which  process  I  would  evolve  a  very 
different  complex  idea  of  man,  as  in  Ethics,  for  example,  than  would 
be  the  case  if  I  only  consider  him  in  the  light  of  some  other  end, 
that  view  of  him  as  embraced  by  the  idea  actor  or  soldier.  "  If  there- 
fore, any  one  will  think  that  a  man,  and  a  horse,  and  an  animal,  and 
a  plant,  etc.,  are  distinguished  by  real  essences  made  by  nature,  he 
must  think  nature  to  be  very  liberal  of  these  real  essences,  making 
one  for  body,  another  for  an  animal,  and  another  for  a  horse,  and 
all  these  essences  liberally  bestowed  upon  Bucephalus.  But  if  we 
would  rightly  consider  what  is  done  in  all  these  genera  and  species, 
or  sorts,  we  should  find  that  there  is  no  new  thing  made,  but  only 
more  or  less  comprehensive  signs,  whereby  we  may  be  enabled  to 
express  in  a  few  syllables  great  numbers  of  particular  things,  as 
they  agree  in  more  or  less  general  conceptions,  which  we  have  framed 
to  that  purpose."  27  Hence  Locke's  conclusion,  that  "  the  essence 
of  each  sort  is  the  abstract  idea,"  2S  understanding  by  essence,  that 
"measure  and  boundary  of  each  sort  or  species  whereby  it  is  con- 
stituted that  particular  sort  and  distinguished  from  others.  ...  So 
that  the  essential  and  not  essential  relates  only  to  our  abstract  ideas ; 
which  amounts  to  no  more  than  this,  that  whatever  particular  thing 
has  not  in  it  those  qualities  which  are  contained  in  the  abstract  idea 
which  any  general  term  stands  for,  cannot  be  ranked  under  that 
species  nor  be  called  by  that  name,"'29  not  any  more  so  than  "  that 
particular  parcel  of  matter  which  makes  the  ring  on  my  finger" 

2<>.  Ibid.,  sec.  4. 

27.  Ibid.,  sec.  32. 

28.  Ibid.,  sec.  2. 

29.  Ibid.,  sees.  2-4. 


70 

may  be  called  gold  and  held  to  possess  the  essence  of  gold,  unless 
that  particular  parcel  of  matter  is  either  actually  or  potentially  all 
that  my  complex  idea  of  gold  stands  for.  "  Should  there  be  found  a 
parcel  of  matter  that  had  all  the  other  qualities  that  are  in  iron,  but 
wanted  obedience  to  the  loadstone,  would  any  one  question  whether 
it  wanted  anything  essential  ?  It  would  be  absurd  to  ask  whether  a 
thing  really  existing  wanted  anything  essential  to  it;  nor  could  it 
be  demanded  whether  this  made  an  essential  or  specific  difference  or 
not,  since  we  have  no  other  measure  of  essential  or  specific  but  our 
abstract  idea  ?  And  to  talk  of  specific  differences  in  nature,  without 
reference  to  general  ideas  in  names,  is  to  talk  unintelligibly;  .  .  . 
all  such  patterns  and  standards  being  quite  laid  aside,  particular 
beings,  considered  barely  in  themselves,  will  be  found  to  have  all 
their  qualities  equally  essential;  and  everything  in  each  individual 
will  be  essential  to  it,  or,  which  is  more,  nothing  at  all.  For 
though  it  may  be  reasonable  to  ask,  whether  obeying  the  magnet 
be  essential  to  iron?  yet  I  think  it  is  very  improper  and  insignifi- 
cant to  ask,  whether  it  be  essential  to  the  particular  parcel  of  matter 
I  cut  my  pen  with,  without  considering  it  under  the  name  iron,  or 
as  being  of  a  certain  species?  .  .  .  Hence  we  find  many  of  the 
individuals  that  are  ranked  into  one  sort,  called  by  one  common 
name,  and  so  received  as  being  of  one  species,  have  yet  qualities, 
depending  on  their  real  constitutions,  as  far  different  one  from 
another  as  from  others  from  which  they  are  accounted  to  differ 
specifically."  30 

If  then  the  essence  or  specific  denomination  or  meaning  of  each 
particular  thing  refers  to  its  determination  within  some  complex 
idea,  what  in  the  constitution  of  things  is  sufficient  to  justify  the 
formation  of  a  new  sort  or  species  ?  We  distinguish  between  watches 
and  clocks  as  distinct  sorts,  yet  the  variation  among  watches  is 
large  just  as  it  is  among  clocks ; 31  or  we  distinguish  between 
water  when  liquid  and  frozen,  designating  the  former  water  and  the 
latter,  ice,  and  yet  fail  to  do  so  in  the  case  of  congealed  jelly,  when 
it  is  cold  and  the  same  jelly  fluid  and  warm ;  or  in  the  case  of  liquid 
gold  in  the  furnace  and  hard  gold  in  the  hands  of  a  workman.32 
This  situation  Locke  suggests,  but  he  does  not  elaborate  it.  This  is 
much  to  be  regretted,  for  Locke  in  that  case  would  have  been  led 
to  transfer  his  present  contention  into  the  very  citadel  of  his  dogma : 
nothing  exists  but  particulars ;  for  ice  and  water  denote  two  particu- 

30.  Ibid.,  sees.  5-8. 

31.  See  Ibid.,  sec.  39. 

32.  Ibid.,  sec.  13. 


71 

lars ;  why  not  so  in  the  case  of  gold  or  jelly?  All  I  can  find  in 
Book  III,  as  in  any  way  pertinent  to  the  issue,  is,  that  shape,  in 
the  case  of  vegetables  and  animals,  and  color,  in  respect  to  bodies 
not  propagated  by  seed,  are  the  aspects  of  things  we  most  fix  on  and 
;i  re  most  led  by.33  In  his  account  of  mixed  modes,  as  may  be  recalled, 
he  enters  upon  this  particular  inquiry  more  fully.  But  in  respect  to 
substances,  his  interest  rarely  strays  beyond  the  locus  of  the  follow- 
ing inquiry :  things  are  determined  and  held  fixed  to  their 
specific  sorts  by  their  abstract  ideas,  whereby  particular  things, 
"  because  they  have  that  nominal  essence,  which  is  all  one,  agree  to 
that  abstract  idea  a  name  is  annexed  to,"  3*  come  to  be  of  this  or 
that  sort,  and  so,  as  we  read  here  and  there,  "  has  in  truth  a  refer- 
ence not  so  much  to  the  being  of  particular  things,  as  to  their  gen- 
eral denominations."  35  But  this  is  but  one  conclusion ;  another : 
"  take  but  away  the  abstract  ideas  by  which  we  sort  individuals,  and 
rank  them  under  common  names,  and  then  the  thought  of  anything 
essential  to  any  of  them  instantly  vanishes;  we  have  no  notion  of 
the  one  without  the  other,  which  plainly  shows  their  relation.36 
.  .  .  For  to  talk  of  a  man,  and  to  lay  by,  at  the  same  time,  the 
ordinary  signification  of  the  name  man,  which  is  our  complex  idea 
usually  annexed  to  it,  and  bid  the  reader  consider  man  as  he  is  in 
himself,  and  as  he  is  really  distinguished  from  others  .  .  .  looks 
like  trifling."  37  "  Nothing  essential  to  individuals,"  38  is  the  claim 
he  here  sets  up,  as  it  were,  to  confront  his  familiar  dogma :  "  noth- 
ing exists  but  particulars  " :  and  his  solution,  as  noted,  appears  to 
be  twofold:  sorts  relate  "not  so  much  to  the  being  of  particular 
things,  as  to  their  denomination  " ;  and  the  opposite  one,  that  to 
"  bid  the  reader  consider  man  as  he  is  in  himself,  as  he  is  really 
distinguished  from  others,"  apart  from  our  sort-view  of  him, 
"  looks  like  trifling."  It  is  true,  he  goes  on  to  say,  "  that  I  have 
often  mentioned  a  real  essence,  distinct  in  substance  from  those 
abstract  ideas  of  them,  which  I  call  their  nominal  essence.  By  this 
real  essence  I  mean  the  real  constitution  of  anything,  which  is  the 
foundation  of  all  those  properties  that  are  combined  in  it,  and  are 
constantly  found  to  co-exist  with  the  nominal  essence;  that  par- 
ticular constitution  which  everything  has  within  itself,  without  any 
relation  to  anything  without  it.  But  essence  ('  measure  and  bound- 

33.  Ibid.  sec.  29. 

34.  Ibid.  sec.  7. 

35.  Ibid.  sec.   8.     Italics  mine. 

36.  Ibid.  sec.  4. 

37.  Ibid.  sec.  43. 

38.  Ibid.  sec.  4. 


72 

ary?),  even  in  this  sense  relates  to  a  sort,  and  supposes  a  species; 
for  being  that  real  constitution  on  which  the  properties  depend,  it 
(the  '  real  essence')  necessarily  supposes  a  sort  of  things,  prop- 
erties belonging  only  to  species  and  not  to  individuals."  39  That  is 
to  say,  even  if  we  grant  "  essential  differences  in  nature  between 
particulars/'  the  particular  would  be  as  much  an  intellectualized 
thing,  if  we  get  beyond  mere  empty  words,  as  the  "  sort,"  For  to 
talk  of  particulars,  in  so  far  as  they  are  particular,  implies  that 
they  have  something  which  belongs  to  them  in  their  own  right,  and 
accordingly  involve  a  principle  of  inclusion  and  exclusion  of  certain 
specific  determinations.  That  is,  certain  properties  are  affirmed  as 
essentially  true  of  it,  others  denied  as  constituting  a  part  of  it.  But 
Locke's  conclusion  is :  "  There  is  no  individual  parcel  of  matter  to 
which  any  of  its  qualities  are  so  annexed  as  to  be  essential  to  it  or 
inseparable  from  it,  That  which  is  essential,  belongs  to  it  as  a  condi- 
tion, whereby  it  is  of  this  or  that  sort ;  but  take  away  the  considera- 
tion of  its  being  ranked  under  the  name  of  some  abstract  idea,  and 
then  there  is  nothing  necessary  to  it,  nothing  separable  from  it."  40 
Namely,  the  principle  of  inclusion  and  exclusion  of  parts  presup- 
poses and  involves  comparison,  unless  some  inherent  real  essence, 
as  existing  and  as  discoverable,  furnishes  us  with  the  needed  prin- 
ciple. And  Locke's  arguments  on  this  point  assumes  two  forms : 
(a)  the  ungrounded  character  for  even  assuming  that  such  real 
essences  exist,  by  seeking  to  exhibit  a  diversity  even  among  our 
particular  parcels  of  matter,  as  well  as  among  a  supposed  natural 
animal  and  vegetable  species;  and  (b),  by  the  further  claim,  that 
even  if  real  essences  did  exist,  we  do  not  know  them  and  never  can 
know  them.  The  conclusion  is  reinforced  by  the  relativistic  prin- 
ciple either  in  its  empirical  or  radical  form:  isolate  a  piece  of  gold 
from  all  other  bodies  and  it  reduces  to  zero,  for  not  only  substances 
(in  the  nominal  sense)  but  objects  or  bodies  in  general  "  are  but 
powers,  either  active  or  passive,  in  reference  to  other  bodies."  41 
Locke's  confusion  arises  in  confounding  the  ontological  particular, 
which  seems  to  resist  death  at  all  cost,  with  "  a  particular  parcel  of 
matter,"  and  then  again  seeking  to  distinguish  the  former  from  the 
latter.  In  either  case,  however,  we  have  his  contention  that  particu- 
lars are  variable  and  indeterminate  until  made  determinate  by,  and 
held  fixed  in  our  abstract  idea  of  them.  Summarized,  the  following, 

39.  Ibid.,  sec.  6.     Italics  are  mine. 

40.  Ibid. 

41.  Ibid.,  ch.  9,  sec,  17.     This  principle  has  such  frequent  restatement 
in  Locke,  that  any  special  references  are  needless.    In  particular,  read  ch.  9, 
Bk.  Ill;    ch.  31,  Bk.  II;    and  ch.  6,  sees.  11-12,  Bk.  IV. 


73 

then,  presents  Locke's  position:  he  assumes  an  interplay  of  rela- 
tions or  parts,  that  reflects  itself  in  breaking -down  or  altering  par- 
ticulars or  in  building  them  up  and  preserving  them  thus,  at  least 
relatively  so;  for  relations  are  as  capable  of  neutralizing  each 
other's  effects  as  they  are  capable  of  reinforcing  them.  Hence  the 
justification  and  rational  basis  of  Locke's  empirical  relativity: 
"  bodies  "  are  capable  of  producing  change  in  or  receiving  it  from 
other  "bodies"  to  an  indefinite  degree.  But  bodies  as  of  this  or 
that  sort,  or  of  this  or  that  determination,  involve  the  abstract  idea, 
which,  in  turn,  involves  and  presupposes  analysis,  comparison,  and 
synthesis,  with  the  outcome  in  the  form  of  the  more  "general 
abstract  idea  "  or  the  more  "  particular  abstract  idea."  "  Nature," 
to  which  we  must  turn  in  the  formation  of  our  complex  idea  of 
substances,  offers  "  similitudes  "  and  also  parts  in  "  constant  and 
inseparable  union " ;  hence,  offers  "  parts  in  union,"  complexes, 
as  real,  as  ultimate,  and  as  final  as  parts  in  union,  as  any  of  its 
parts  viewed  in  the  light  of  simple  ideas.  And  these  parts  "  in 
union,"  however  partial  or  variable  the  parts  "  in  union,"  constitute 
the  data  upon  which  the  abstract  ideas,  in  their  formation,  are 
shown  dependent.  "  Apart  from  our  abstract  ideas,  no  determina- 
tion in  our  objects,"  thus  gets  its  complement  stated  as  well: 
"  apart  from  determinations,  however  variable  or  partial,  in  our 
particular  parcels  of  matter  in  this  or  that  specific  situation,  no 
determination  of  our  abstract  ideas." 

This  doctrine  in  Locke  I  designate  as  a  phase  of  his  constructive 
relativity,  and  I  request  any  one  to  show  me  a  doctrine  in  his  pages, 
which  in  its  comprehensive  survey  can  match  itself  with  this  one. 
In  his  elaboration  of  it,  he  accepts  his  simple  ideas  as  such  "  parts," 
but  he  goes  further,  in  the  claim  that  the  union  of  parts,  although 
no  taste,  smell,  color,  etc.,  is  as  much  of  the  nominal  essence  as  the 
simple  ideas  of  sensuous  perception.  Such  union  represents  noth- 
ing that  is  "  visible,"  but  it  notwithstanding  implies  that  sequence, 
co-existence,  change,  succession  are  perceived  facts;  so  real,  that 
to  talk  of  complex  ideas  as  otherwise  complex,  is  wilful  perversion. 
Hence  his  admission,  as  quoted  in  a  previous  chapter,  "  that  our 
ideas  of  extension,  duration,  and  number,  do  they  not  all  contain  in 
them  a  secret  relation  of  the  parts?  Figure  and  motion  have  some- 
thing relative  in  them  much  more  visibly;  and  sensible  qualities, 
as  color  and  smell,  etc.,  what  are  they  but  the  powers  of  different 
bodies  in  relation  to  our  perception,  etc?  .  .  .  Our  idea  therefore 
of  power  (which  includes  in  it  also  some  kind  of  relation,  a  relation 


74 

to  action  or  change),  I  think  may  well  have  a  place  amongst  other 
simple  ideas,  and  be  considered  as  one  of  them/'  *2  His  notion  of 
substances  as  facts,  and  not  mere  illusions  and  deceptions,  involves 
the  same  conclusion :  the  union  of  its  parts  is  as  real  and  ultimate 
as  the  parts  themselves.  In  fact,  in  the  above  passage,  in  order 
to  establish  the  reality  of  modes,  his  deliberate  effort  and  lack  of 
hesitancy  to  resolve  "  sensible  qualities "  themselves  into  sheer 
relations  (no  mere  passing  procedure  with  him)  must  look  as  a 
very  interesting  procedure,  indeed,  to  one  saturated  with  the  notion 
that  Locke  is  fundamentally  a  sensationalist  and  not  a  relativist. 

42.  Bk.  11,  ch.  21,  sec.  3.    Italics  are  mine. 


CHAPTER  X 


DOCTRIXE   OF   ME  AXING 

("Ideas  of  Relation") 

T.  H.  GUI-: EX  laments  that  Locke  "  in  his  account  of  our  complex 
ideas,  explains  them  under  modes,  substances,  and  relations  as  if 
each  of  these  three  sorts  were  independent  of  the  rest."  That  Locke 
never  thoroughly  correlates  them  is  certainly  to  be  regretted,  and 
yet  I  feel  that  Locke  in  actual  practice  is  far  from  keeping  them  as 
independent  of  each  other  as  he,  in  theory,  often  struggles  to  do. 
Thus  it  is  found,  for  example,  that  modes,  substances  and  relations 
are  alike  constructs.  Moreover,  in  our  account  of  mixed  modes, 
we  might  have  asked  wherein  their  declared  dependence  upon 
so-called  Nature  kept  them  distinguished  from  substances,  while 
substances,  in  turn,  reflected  a  dependence  upon  a  very  complex 
process  of  mind  operating  variously  under  very  complex  conditions, 
alike  sensuous  and  non-sensuous  in  composition.  When  we  come  to 
our  "  ideas  of  relations  "  the  overlapping  and  interfusion  is  made 
even  more  apparent.  Not  only  does  all  distinction  between  mixed 
modes  and  relations  practically  vanish,  but  that  between  simple 
modes  and  relations  vanishes  as  well ;  while  substances,  in  general, 
get  themselves  identified,  as  we  have  seen,  with  "  powers  " ;  namely, 
relations,  or,  again,  with  what  is  "  positive  "  and  non-relative.  And 
when  we  deal  with  what  is  "  positive,"  let  us  not  fail  to  recall,  that 
the  real  of  reals  with  Locke  is  "  pleasure  and  pain,  beyond  which 
we  have  no  concernment."  We  ought  not  to  feel  surprised,  there- 
fore, if  in  his  account  of  "ideas  of  relation"  a  unified  rather  than 
a  split-up  world  should  get  itself  more  or  less  clearly  foreshadowed. 
ISTo  man  is  more  dangerously  read  in  snatches  than  Locke. 

In  a  sense,  therefore,  our  present  chapter  may  be  regarded  as  a 
reinstatement  of  the  problem  canvassed  at  large  in  our  previous 
chapter;  namely,  the  interdependence  of  fact  and  idea;  the  sole 
difference  being,  that  there  we  were  supposed  to  be  more  narrowly 

75 


76 

concerned  with  the  sensuous  structure  of  an  object,  and  that  here, 
following  Locke,  we  are  to  be  more  narrowly  concerned  with  its 
abstract  structure  in  terms  of  space,  time,  casuality,  etc.,  and  with 
its  value  structure  in  terms  of  the  "  various  ends,  objects,  manners, 
and  circumstances  of  human  action,"  x  whereby  such  distinctions 
are  acquired  by  them  as  "good,  bad  or  indifferent."  The  term 
Meaning,  in  our  common  use  of  it,  appears  the  one  best  employed  as 
covering  the  situation.  By  adhering  to  this  term,  I  in  no  way 
violate  Locke's  account  and  avoid  considerable  confusion. 

Meaning,  with  Locke,  stands  primarily  for  an  interdependence 
of  objects  as  reflected  in  thought :  "  Beside  the  ideas,  whether 
simple  or  complex,  that  the  mind  has  of  things  as  they  are  in  them- 
selves, there  are  others  it  gets  from  their  comparison  one  with 
another,"  2  whereby  certain  distinctions  or  "  denominations  "  are 
acquired  by  them,  but  not  as  something  "  contained  in  the  real 
existence  of  things,  but  something  extraneous  and  superinduced ;"  3 
that  is,  meaning  is  purely  mental  in  existential  status.  He  holds 
further,  "  that  there  is  no  one  thing  .  .  .  which  is  not  capable  of 
almost  an  infinite  number  of  considerations  in  reference  to  other 
things,"  and  that  meaning  therefore  "  makes  no  small  part  of  men's 
thoughts  and  words ;  v.  g.,  one  single  man  may  at  once  be  concerned 
in  and  sustain  all  these  following  relations  [denominations,  mean- 
ings], and  many  more;  viz.,  father,  brother,  son,  grandfather,  .  .  . 
friend,  enemy,  judge,  patron,  .  .  .  servant,  master,  .  .  .  older, 
younger,  like,  unlike,  etc.,  etc.,  to  an  almost  infinite  number;  he 
being  capable  of  as  many  denominations  as  there  can  be  occasions 
of  comparing  him  to  other  things."  4 

The  view  presented  contains  nothing  novel.  When  an  object  is 
said  to  have  meaning  it  is  not  uncommon  to  hear  it  spoken  of  as 
something  imported  into  the  object  from  without,  and  never,  except 
by  the  idealist,  or  pragmatist  perchance,  viewed  as  an  integral  part 
of  said  object.  But  we  often,  as  Locke  will  be  found  doing,  notwith- 
standing, begin  with  the  consideration  of  meaning  as  actually 
existing  in  an  object,  even  if  in  the  light  of  an  appearance  only,  and 
then,  in  virtue  of  its  more  natural  and  obtrusive  variability  and 
diversity,  hold  it  up  as  something  more  or  less  gratuitously  con- 
tributed from  without.  Relativity  is  rarely  a  disputed  fact  in  this 
realm.  What  is  disputed,  is  whether  meaning  does  become  or  ever 

1.  Bk.  II,  ch.  28,  sec.  4. 

2.  Ibid.,  ch.  25,  sees.  1-7. 

3.  Ibid.,  sec.  8. 

4.  Ibid.,  sec.  7. 


can  become  an  integral  part  of  an  object.  It  exists  in  thought  and 
for  thought  only,  proclaims  the  realist;  it  is  a  distortion  or  falsi- 
fication of  reality,  says  the  naturalist.  But  to  establish  either  of 
their  contentions,,  a  criterion  of  an  object  is  presupposed.  What 
that  is  in  their  case,  I  leave  for  them  to  decipher.  I  accept  for  my 
object  Locke's  object  as  presented  in  the  previous  chapter.  Locke, 
too,  must  be  expected  to  abide  by  it,  and  the  doctrine,  just  outlined, 
scanned  in  the  light  of  it. 

In  accord  with  his  notion  of  an  object  as  a  construct,  we  were 
not  only  said  to  be  allowed,  but  constrained,  to  fix  upon  the  specific 
character  of  our  object  with  a  variation  of  content,  and,  as  once 
defined  and  articulated,  invited  to  deny,  if  we  choose,  that  any 
further  qualification  of  it  is  relevant.  But,  then,  in  denying  such 
relevancy,  as  we  were  further  shown,  another  ground  for  deciding 
the  matter  had  to  be  found  than  is  offered  in  the  variable  and 
potential  qualities  of  the  object  itself.  If  an  object,  in  accord  with 
relativity,  gets  to  be  what  it  is  solely  in  and  through  its  relations  to 
other  objects,  and  such  relations  affirmed  to  be  indefinite,  if  not 
wholly  infinite,  then  the  modifications  manifested  in  an  object 
cannot  be  designated  as  real  and  valid  in  respect  to  its  so-called 
"  powers,"  but  mere  appearances  and  superinductions  when  acquired 
in  the  character  of  meaning.  It  is  not  logic  to  blow  hot  and  cold 
with  the  same  principle.  Locke  cannot  revert  to  the  dogmas  of  the 
realist  or  naturalist  as  he  is  apparently  seen  to  do  in  the  above, 
nor  shall  we  be  found  under  any  special  obligation  to  halt,  with 
thai  view  of  the  matter. 

But  the  objection  may  be  raised  that,  in  respect  to  sorts,  the 
mutual  determination  of  objects  was  of  a  mechanical  type ;  whereas 
here  we  are  dealing  with  mutual  determinations  as  essentially 
mental.  To  this  objection  I  need  only  subjoin  that  causality,  the 
so-termed  mechanical  type  of  determination,  is  but  one  of  Locke's 
general  types  of  relation  included  and  elaborated  in  this  particular 
division  of  his  work.  In  fact,  to  grasp  the  full  sweep  and  con- 
structive character  of  the  present  doctrine  in  Locke,  we  must  not 
fail  to  keep  in  mind  that  it  is  here  at  length  that  we  get  his  modes, 
whether  simple  or  complex,  correlated  with  substances.  And  thus 
considered,  is  it  necessary  to  ask  who  got  closer  to  Locke,  Kant  or 
Hume?  Locke's  signal  contribution  however  consists  in  the  fact 
that  he  correlated  his  mixed  modes  with  substances  as  well  as  the 
simple  modes,  of  time,  place,  etc.  In  following  Locke  here,  prag- 
matism or  Humanism  have  in  Locke  their  antecedent  in  modern 
thought. 


78 

Leaving  mere  theory,  then,  for  the  moment,  let  us  instead 
direct  attention  to  the  facts  adduced  in  support  of  it.  Interdepen- 
dence of  fact  and  meaning,  is  the  contention  I  seek  to  establish; 
namely,  that  meaning  is  grounded  in  fact,  just  as  in  the  previous 
chapter  its  converse  constituted  our  thesis. 


OBJECTS    AND    MEANING    FOREIGN    TO    EACH    OTHER 

1.  "  Relations     (denominations)     different    from    the    Things 
related."  5      Denominations  may  be  the  same  in  men  "  who  have 
very  different  ideas  of  the  things  that  are  related,  or  that  are  thus 
compared;   v.  g.,  those  who  have  far  different  ideas  of  a  man  may 
yet  agree  in  the  notion  of  a  father ;  which  is  a  notion  superinduced 
to  the  substance,  or  man,  and  refers  only  to  an  act  of  that  tiling, 
called  man,  whereby  he  contributed  to  the  generation  of  one  of  his 
own  kind ;  let  man  be  what  he  will."  6    But  if  it  "  refers  to  an  act 
of  that  thing,"  how  does  meaning  fail  to  constitute  an  integral  part 
of  it  ?    But  this  observation  by  the  way  ! 

2.  Hence,  "  change  of  relation  (denomination)  may  be  without 
any  change  in  the  object, — Caius,  whom  I  consider  to-day  as  a 
father,  ceases  to  be  so  to-morrow  only  by  the  death  of  his  son,  with- 
out any  alteration  made  in  himself.     Xay,  barely  by  the  mind's 
changing  the  object  to  which  it  compares  anything,  the  same  thing 
is  capable  of  having  contrary  denominations  at  the  same  time; 
v.  g.,  Caius,  compared  to  several  persons,  may  truly  be  said  to  be 
older  and  younger,  stronger  and  weaker,  etc."  7 

3.  Meanings  seemingly  inherent  in  objects,   "  conceal  a  tacit 
though  less  observable  relation  " ;  that  is,  show  a  dependence  upon 
something  else;    hence  reduce  to  the  order  of  products;    reveal 
themselves   detachable;    and,   therefore,   can  in  no  way  properly 
belong  to  an  object.    I  proceed  to  quote  from  the  text  without  criti- 
cism or  registered  protest.     That  is  to  follow. 

"  Time  and  place  are  also  the  foundation  of  very  large  relations, 
and  all  finite  beings  at  least  are  concerned  in  them,  .  .  .  but  it 
may  suffice  here  to  intimate,  that  most  of  the  denominations  of 
things  received  from  time  are  only  relations.  Thus,  when  any  one 
says  that  Queen  Elizabeth  lived  sixty-nine  and  reigned  forty-five 
years,  these  words  impart  only  the  relation  of  that  duration  to  some 

5.  Ibid.,  ch.  25,  sec.  4. 

6.  Ibid.,  sec.  4.     Italics  mine. 

7.  Ibid.,  sec.  5. 


79 

other,  and  mean  no  more  than  this,  that  the  duration  of  her  exist- 
ence was  equal  to  sixty-nine,  and  the  duration  of  her  government  to 
forty-five  annual  revolutions  of  the  sun ;  and  so  are  all  words  answer- 
ing, How  long  ?  "  8  Such  words  as  young  and  old  are,  ordinarily,  also 
thought  to  stand  for  positive  ideas,  which,  when  considered,  will  be 
found  to  be  relative;  that  is,  intimate  preconceived  ideas,  formed 
under  specialized  and  limited  conditions.  "  Thus,  having  settled  in 
our  thoughts  the  idea  of  the  ordinary  duration  of  a  man  to  be 
seventy  years,  when  we  say  a  man  is  young,  we  mean  that  his  age  is 
yet  but  a  small  part  of  that  which  men  usually  attain  to;  and 
when  we  denominate  him  old,  we  mean  that  his  duration  is  run  out 
almost  to  the  end  of  that  which  men  do  not  usually  exceed.  And 
so  it  is  comparing  the  particular  age  or  duration  of  this  or  that  man, 
to  the  idea  of  that  duration  which  we  have  in  our  minds,  as  ordi- 
narily belonging  to  that  sort  of  animal ;  which  is  plain,  in  the  appli- 
cation of  these  names  to  other  things;  for  a  man  is  called  young  at 
twenty  years  and  very  young  at  seven  years  old ;  but  a  horse  we  call 
old  at  twenty  and  a  dog  at  seven  years,  because  in  each  of  these  we 
compare  their  age  to  different  ideas  of  duration  which  are  settled 
in  our  minds."  9 

That  meaning  is  an  aspect  in  objects  distinguishable  from  its 
sensuous  quality,  no  one  would  deny.  But  beyond  this  very  general 
distinction,  the  view  of  an  object  as  a  construct  presupposes  the 
presence  of  intellectual  principles  at  every  point.  And  its  saturation 
from  this  source  penetrates  to  its  core  and  is  no  mere  thing  sticking 
loosely  at  the  surface,  ready  to  be  peeled  off  by  any  such  process  as 
was  instituted  above.  Meaning  comes  into  being,  his  illustrations 
would  denote,  by  the  consideration  of  some  positive  object  under 
some  specific  idea  or  other  "  settled  in  our  minds."  That  is,  apart 
from  some  abstract  idea,  no  meaning  in  objects  is  possible.  This  we 
will  grant,  but  only  after  being  instructed  where  those  "ideas  settled 
in  the  mind  "  originate.  They  would  seem  to  arise,  judging  from 
these  very  same  illustrations,  from  more  or  less  definite  and  con- 
crete situations.  In  fact,  these  illustrations  definitely  emphasize 
the  point  that  age,  youth,  size,  etc.,  are  pure  abstractions  where  it  is 
not  the  age,  youth  or  size  or  a  particular  thing  in  a  particular  situa- 
tion with  its  particular  conditions  and  limitations  all  held  together 
in  one  elaborated  notion  or  construct.  Let  us  term  the  point  of  his 
departure,  in  this  general  analysis,  pure  objectivity,  and  then  let 
any  man  tell,  if  he  can,  where  the  contribution  made  by  any  of  its 

8.  Ibid.,  ch.  26,  sec.  3. 

9.  Ibid.,  sec.  4. 


80 

abstracted  elements  begins  or  lets  off  and  where  that  of  its  other 
abstracted  elements  begins  or  lets  off.  In  his  chapters  on  relation, 
Locke  moves  in  this  purely  objective  status  of  existence,  and  seeks 
to  disrupt  it  by  the  introduction  of  his  abstract  realistic  object  on 
the  one  hand,  and  by  the  introduction  of  an  equally  depleted 
abstract  idea  on  the  other.  But  even  from  the  passages  quoted  in  this 
chapter,  the  peculiar  novelty  of  them  all  lies  in  the  fact  that  abstract 
ideas  are  here  revealed  as  growing  out  of  concrete  situations,  "  and 
that  we  are  not  to  wonder  that  we  comprehend  them  not,  and  do  so 
often  find  our  thought  at  a  loss,  when  we  would  consider  them 
abstractly  by  themselves/7  as  he  wrote  in  connection  with  his  account 
of  space  and  time  in  a  passage  adduced  above.10  Had  Locke  only 
followed  out  this  notion  and  continued  his  inquiry  from  it  and 
from  these  admirable  beginnings,  instead  from  the  standpoint  of 
his  abstractions  of  particulars  and  thought  in  divorce ;  or  from  his 
abstractions  of  simple  ideas  versus  complex;  or  from  the  still 
further  abstractions  within  complex  ideas ;  namely,  those  of  simple 
and  complex  modes  versus  substances, — what  a  length  of  needless, 
fruitless  wanderings  Locke  might  have  spared  himself,  and,  further, 
have  spared  the  identification  of  pure  objectivity,  among  some  of  his 
successors,  with  that  range  of  experience  which  we  in  a  protoplasmic 
state  of  existence  might  be  thought  to  have. 

Now  there  is  no  doubt  that  "  the  ideas  settled  in  our  minds  " 
may  vary  with  each  other  in  two  fundamental  respects :  (a)  in  their 
degree  of  possible  generality,  and  ( b )  in  their  degree  of  response  to 
"  the  constant  and  regular  order  of  things  "  or,  on  the  other  hand, 
in  their  degree  of  response  to  a  more  or  less  arbitrary  fancy  or 
imagination.  In  the  latter  distinction,  only,  is  the  ground  to  be 
found  for  the  supposed  distinction  between  purely  mental  deter- 
minations versus  the  more  conspicuously  mechanical.  But  let 
these  distinctions  be  forced  as  hard  as  they  will,  the  distinctions, 
notwithstanding,  are  things  of  degree  and  not  of  kind.  To  establish 
the  fact  that  such  is  Locke's  contention  when  unfettered  by  false 
theory,  I  shall,  in  addition  to  what  has  been  stated,  consider  two 
fundamental  types  of  relation,  that  of  cause  and  effect,  and  that 
of  morality. 

10.  Chapter  4. 


81 


ORIGIN"   OF   OUR  PRECONCEIVED   IDEAS   AND   THEIR 
PROPER   CORRELATION   WITH   FACT-REALITY 

1.    CAUSE    AND    EFFECT 

"  As  it  would  take  a  volume  to  go  over  all  sorts  of  relations 
[preconceived  ideas] ,"  writes  Locke,  "  it  is  not  to  be  expected  that 
I  should  here  mention  them  all."  "  He  proposes,  however,  to 
consider  "  the  most  comprehensive  relation,  wherein  all  things 
that  do  or  can  exist,  are  concerned,  and  that  is  the  relation  of 
cause  and  effect."  I  shall  in  my  account  of  this  relation  freely 
turn  to  every  part  of  his  text  where  this  subject  of  causality  conies 
up  for  discussion.  Space,  time,  identity  and  diversity,  quanti- 
tative, qualitative,  blood,  instituted,  moral,  civil,  and  divine  rela- 
tions, are  the  few  others  Jie  touches  upon,  briefly  or  at  length, 
among  the  "  innumerable  sorts  "  which  "  would  take  a  volume  "  to 
exhaust.  And  the  general  contention  that  concerns  us  is,  that 
relations  have  no  status  or  reality  in  objects,  and,  secondly,  leave 
tli em  accordingly  unaffected,  and  it  is  this  contention  I  seek  to 
refute  in  Locke's  own  words. 

"  There  must  always  in  relation  be  two  ideas  or  things,"  writes 
Locke,  "  either  in  themselves  really  separate,  or  considered  as  dis- 
tinct, and  then  a  ground  or  occasion  for  their  comparison " ; 12 
namely,  all  relation  involves  three  distinct  factors.  Hence  in  the 
matter  of  cause  and  effect,  "taking  notice  how  one  (thing)  comes 
to  an  end  and  ceases  to  be,  and  another  begins  to  exist  which  was 
not  before,"  13  .  .  .  whatever  change  is  thus  observed,  the  mind 
must  collect  a  power  somewhere  able  to  make  that  change,  as  well 
as  a  possibility  in  the  thing  itself  to  receive  it."  14  Here  then  we 
have  '  a/  our  original  idea,  '  b/  a  distinct  perception  of  something 
new  in  that  original  idea,  and  (  c/  the  need  of  the  mind  to  collect 
a  power  somewhere.  My  aim  is  to  search  for  the  ground  of  that 
need,  as  scattered  passages  in  Locke  favor  its  articulation.  With- 

11.  Bk.  II,  ch.  28,  sec.  17. 
.12.  Bk.  II,  ch.  25,  sec.  6. 
/13.  Ibid.,  ch.  21,  sec.  1. 
14.  Ibid.,  sec.  4. 


82 

out  the  ideas  '  a '  and  '  b '  discoverable  as  distinct,  as  "  either  in 
themselves  separate  or  considered  as  distinct/'  the  possibility  of  a 
comparison  would  not  even  exist.  But,  then,  the  present  com- 
parison is  of  a  kind  involving  something  unique.  That  element 
of  uniqueness  is  change.  Change  would  seem  to  be  a  product  of 
thought  induced  by  the  fact  that  '  a  ?  and  '  b/  although  distinct 
or  separate,  hence  Many,  are  yet  constrained  by  thought  to  be  held 
in  the  original  Oneness ;  for  we  begin  with  '  a/  which  is  One,  and 
yet  forced  to  perceive  '  b '  as  another,  when  it  comes  "  to  exist 
which  was  not  before."  Yet  "  we  never  finding  nor  conceiving  it 
possible,  that  two  things  of  the  same  kind  should  exist  in  the  same 
place  at  the  same  time,  we  rightly  conclude  that  whatever  exists 
anywhere  at  any  time  excludes  all  of  the  same  kind  and  is  there 
itself  alone.  .  .  .  (But  further)  since  one  thing  cannot  have  two 
beginnings  of  existence,  nor  two  things  one  beginning :  it  is  impos- 
sible for  two  things  .  .  .  to  be  or  exist  in  the  same  instant,  in  the 
very  same  place,  or  one  and  the  same  thing  in  different  places. 
That,  therefore,  that  had  one  beginning,  is  the  same  thing;  and 
that  which  had  a  different  beginning  in  time  and  place  from  that, 
is  not  the  same,  but  diverse."  15  In  other  words,  '  b  3  having  broke 
out  as  separate  and  distinct  from  '  a/  they  cannot  as  two  distinct 
things,  have  the  same  single  beginning  able  to  account  for  both 
of  them ;  hence  the  need  of  the  mind  to  collect  a  beginning  for  ( b  ' 
somewhere.  But  where  turn  for  the  originating  principle  where 
"  powers  are  relations  and  not  agents,"  16  and  the  "  communication 
of  motion  by  impulse,  or  by  thought  [the  only  possible  agents]  are 
equally  .  .  .  obscure  and  inconceivable.  .  .  .  We  have  by  daily 
experience  clear  evidence  of  motion  produced  both  by  impulse  and 
thought;  but  the  manner  how,  hardly  comes  within  our  compre- 
hension; we  are  equally  at  a  loss  in  both.  .  .  .  For.  when  the  mind 
would  look  beyond  those  original  ideas  we  have  from  sensation  or 
reflection,  and  penetrate'  into  their  causes,  and  manner  of  produc- 
tion, we  find  it  discovers  nothing  but  its  own  shortsightedness; 
.  .  .  there  is  no  more  difficulty  to  conceive  how  a  substance,  we 
know  not,  should,  by  thought,  set  body  in  motion,  than  how  a 
substance,  we  know  not,  by  impulse,  set  body  into  motion."  17  Yet 
the  mind  is  constrained  "  to  collect  a  power  somewhere/'  even 
though  it  has  no  visible  fulcrum  to  rest  upon;  for  change  implies 
a  new  existence  in  space  and  time,  or  in  time  only,  and  the  new 

15.  Ibid.,  ch.  27,  sec.  1. 

16.  Ibid.,  ch.  21,  sec.  19. 

17.  Ibid.,  ch.  23,  sees.  28-29. 


83 

thing  (  b '  must  get  itself  correlated  or  a  "  beginning  "  somehow  or 
other.  The  need  is  as  real  ( 1 )  as  the  perception  of  '  a '  and  '  b ' 
as  distinct  existences  is  real;  (2)  as  real  as  the  idea  of  change,  as 
the  result  of  the  compa.rison;  (that  is,  as  real  as  the  original  unity 
and  subsequent  diversity  is  real)  ;  (3)  as  real  as  the  principle  of 
eonservation  :  and  (4)  as  real  as  the  inherent  intellectual  need 
for  unity  in  our  experience.  In  a  word,  cause  and  effect  is  a 
thought  construct,  involving  comparison  on  the  basis  of  a  real 
il-irrrxili/  in  unify,  and  the  postulate  that  every  new  existence 
involves  the  idea  of  a  new  beginning;  something  cannot  come  out 
of  nothing.  Such  then  would  seem  the  origin  of  our  "precon- 
ceived idea  "  of  cause  and  effect.  It  certainly  does  not  appear  as  if 
generated  in  a  vacuum,  but  in  an  exceedingly  complex  situation, 
wherein  the  interpretation  of  fact  and  idea  or  meaning  appears  so 
complete  as  well  nigh  to  baffle  analysis. 

'  I'nity  '  is  another  such  idea.  Shall  we  call  it  fact  or  meaning? 
And  if  meaning,  shall  we  hold  it  as  ungrounded  in  reality  and  as 
leaving  it  unaffected,  "  it  sufficing  to  the  unity  of  an  idea  [object]/' 
as  Locke  writes,  "  that  it  be  considered  as  one  representation  or 
picture,  though  made  up  of  ever  so  many  particulars"?18  Under 
conditions  then,  "  an  army,  a  swarm,  a  city,  a  fleet,"  are  "  things 
as  perfectly  one  as  one  ship  or  one  atom."  19  That  reality  is  not 
left  unaffected  by  it,  is  here  evident.  But  is  such  unity  real?  Yes, 
if  it  serves  our  ends,  or  works;  for  after  all,  as  Locke's  recurrent 
note  would  have  it:  "  God  has  fitted  us  for  the  neighborhood  of 
the  bodies  that  surround  us"20  .  .  .  and  "it  will  become  us,  as 
rational  creatures,  to  employ  those  faculties  we  have  about  what 
they  are  most  adopted  to."21  Ideas,  then,  that  work  successfully 
in  our  efforts  to  comprehend  the  world,  and  in  our  general  lack  of 
others  or  better,  are  real;  it  being  as  real  in  the  interest  of  some 
ends,  to  regard  a  fleet  or  a  city  as  One  and  not  as  Many,  as  in  the 
interest  of  other  ends  to  do  the  reverse.  Fact  and  meaning  are 
on<\  and,  at  best,  distinguishable  Aspects  only. 

18.  Ibid.,  ch.  24,  sec.  1. 

19.  Ibid.,  ch.  24,  sec.  2. 

20.  Ibid.,  ch.  16,  sec.  13. 

21.  Bk.  IV,  ch.  12,  sees.  10-11. 


2.    MORAL    RELATIONS 

"  Virtue  and  vice/7  writes  Locke,  "are  names  supposed  every- 
where to  stand  for  actions  in  their  own  nature  right  and  wrong."2 
This  position,  in  harmony  with  his  general  contention,  Locke  denies, 
and,  in  turn,  sets  up  the  contention,  "  that  moral  good  and  evil 
consist  in  nothing  but  the  conformity  of  our  voluntary  actions  to 
some  law ;  which,  I  think,  may  he  called  moral  relation,  as  being 
that  which  denominates  our  moral  actions  ...  which  relation  as 
a  touchstone,  serves  to  set  the  mark  of  value  upon  their  voluntary 
actions."  23  The  following  illustration  sums  up  his  whole  position : 
"  Our  actions  are  considered  as  good,  bad,  or  indifferent ;  and  in 
this  respect  they  are  relative,  it  being  their  conformity  to,  or  disa- 
greement with  some  rule  that  makes  them  to  be  regular  or  irreg- 
ular, good  or  bad.  .  .  .  Thus  the  challenging  and  fighting  with 
a  man,  as  it  is  a  certain  positive  mode,  or  particular  sort  of  action 
...  is  called  duelling,  which,  when  considered  in  relation  to  the 
law  of  God,  will  deserve  the  name  sin;  to  the  law  of  fashion,  in 
some  countries,  valor  and  virtue;  and  to  the  municipal  laws  of 
some  governments,  a  capital  crime."  2*  That  is,  apart  from  our 
preconceived  ideas,  no  moral  determinations  in  our  objects.  But 
suppose  we  again  raise  the  counter  claim:  apart  from  determina- 
tions of  some  kind  or  other  in  our  objects,  can  we  attain  to  any 
preconceived  ideas  at  all  ?  And  what  we  find  is,  that  the  disruption 
of  pure  objectivity,  brought  about  by  abstract  distinctions,  is  again 
the  state  of  affairs.  Modes  as  abstract,  as  the  pure  products  of 
Eeason,  a  priori  determinable  therein  apart  from  all  experience  or 
any  direct  check  or  control  from  experience,  is  his  conception  of 
morality  as  that  rule  or  law  whereby,  as  to  a  touchstone,  our  volun- 
tary actions  get  the  marks  of  value  set  upon  them.  Hence  there  is 
no  hope  for  freeing  his  doctrine  here  of  an  abstract  conceptualism, 
unless  Locke  abandons  his  purely  theoretical  dogmatic  view  con- 
cerning modes.  And  on  this  point,  Locke,  in  theory  at  least,  con- 
cedes nothing.  Until  such  a  priori  pretensions  concerning  modes, 
however,  are  abandoned,  the  original  objectivity  of  our  experience 
cannot  be  restored.  This  situation  represents  Locke's  general  posi- 
tion: but  fortunately  it  is  not  an  expression  of  his  sole  utterance. 
For,  if  "  good  and  evil,"  as  Locke  contends,  "  are  nothing  but 

22.  Bk.  II,  ch.  28,  sec.  10.    Italics  are  mine. 

23.  Ibid.,  sees.  4,  5,  14. 

24.  Ibid.,   sec.    15. 


85 

pleasure  or  pain,  or  that  which  occasions  or  procures  pleasure  or 
pain  to  us  " 25  and  our  state,  "  as  fitted  for  the  neighborhood  of 
the  bodies  that  surround  us,"  giving  us  no  concernment  beyond 
either  to  know  or  to  be,  our  "  preconceived  idea  "  will  depend  upon 
a  consideration  of  the  various  factors  able  to  produce  and  suffer 
pleasure  or  pain,  and,  as  thus  considered,  organized  into  a  whole. 
And  with  this  degree  of  a  suggested  reconstruction  of  such  elements 
as  appear  in  his  Essay,  I  think  I  may  let  the  matter  rest.  To 
have  denoted  morality  the  relation  of  actions  to  a  law,  as  he 
does,  and  yet  not  find  that  law  in  those  actions  themselves,  as 
their  expression  in  certain  fundamental  relations,  but,  instead, 
to  find  that  law  the  expression  of  an  abstract  Eeason  divorced 
from  Experience,  reveals  anew  how  deep  Locke,  in  certain  aspects 
of  his  doctrine,  remained  sticking  in  rationalism,  and  by  con- 
trast, reveals  the  vast  strides  made  by  him  in  those  other  phases 
of  his  doctrine.  If,  as  Ethics  tends  to  enforce,  a  man  is  not  truly 
moralized,  whatever  its  values  be,  until  such  values  are  worked 
into  the  very  texture  of  his  being,  I  fail  to  see  how  value  as  a 
class  can  remain  distinctions  "  extraneous  and  superinduced/' 
For  grant  that  the  "  preconceived  idea "  is  involved  at  every 
point  in  an  object's  determination,  as  Locke  insists  upon,  and 
the  "  preconceived  idea  "  little  else  than  the  synthetic  articulation 
of  a  very  complex  situation,  as  Locke  seenis  further  to  maintain, 
then  how  prove  the  validity  of  that  idea  and  its  applicability  as 
well,  without  admitting  at  the  same  time  that  the  object  itself  is 
involved  in  that  situation  in  its  total  compass,  is  more  than  I  can 
Linisp.  The  object  is.  then,  in  fact  and  deed  just  what  it  is  in  that 
situation,  whose  total  rays  or  light  the  preconceived  idea  only 
attempts  to  draw  to  a  point  in  order  to  focus  them  upon  this  or 
that  part  in  the  total  situation,  a  situation  which,  although  realizing 
itself  in  the  idea,  actualizes  itself  in  time  only  and  more  or  less 
piecemeal,  as  set  forth  in  the  previous  chapter.  But  it  is  in  virtue 
of  that  total  only,  widely  or  narrowly  circumscribed  as  the  case  may 
be,  that  any  part  within  it  becomes  of  this  specific  value  or  deter- 
mination rather  than  of  that — a  construct,  no  matter  at  what  point 
we  view  it.  Thus,  if  an  artist  finds  an  object's  particular  soul  and 
pulse  in  its  colors,  who  will  prove  that  he  has  failed  to  get  its  soul 
and  pulse,  save  by  dogmatically  sticking  to  the  claim  that  we  to 
the  contrary,  in  some  other  equally  specialized  view  or  determina- 
tion, have  gotten  such  soul  or  pulse  of  the  objects  about  us, — 

25.  Ibid.,  ch.  28,  sec.  5. 


86 

objects,  by  theory,,  variable  and  indefinite  in  their  determination 
and  signification.  And  if  this  be  true  of  their  more  distinctively 
sensuous  aspect,  how  much  more  so  of  their  meaning-aspect;  that 
is,  if  the  determination  of  substances  (in  Locke's  terminology) 
depends  upon  our  ideas  of  them  variously  formed;  how  much  more 
so  in  the  case  of  the  modes  and  the  relations,  as  he  insists.  But 
the  latter  are  merely  '  extraneous  and  superinduced/  the  realist 
may  persist  in  proclaiming.  Well,  then,  let  him  be  equally  ready 
to  maintain  that  civilization,  with  all  its  distinctions  and  achieve- 
ments, wrought  out  with  the  brain  and  hands  of  man,  and  grounded 
in  the  heart  and  stomach  and  skin,  as  well  as  in  other  assumed 
facts,  are  extraneous  superinductions  upon  a  more  real  abstract 
world.  The  nihilist,  strange  to  say,  champions  the  same  creed, 
and  to  him  art,  morality,  government,  refinement,  culture,  science, 
but  specious  falsification  of  reality.  If  this  is  not  the  logic  of 
realism,  I  have  yet  to  learn  it;  and  if  such  is  not  its  logic,  then 
its  logic  is  that  of  Locke :  "  All  such  patterns  and  standards  laid 
aside,  particular  beings,  considered  barely  in  themselves,  will  be 
found  to  have  all  their  qualities  equally  essential;  and  everything 
in  each  individual  will  be  essential  to  it,  or,  which  is  more,  nothing 
at  all " ; 26  namely,  the  truth  of  reality  is  ideality — "  the  new  way  of 


26.  Bk.  Ill,  ch.  6,  sec.  5. 


CHAPTER  XI 

CONCLUSION 

THE  primacy  of  the  idea  in  the  determination  of  our  objects 
culminates  in  the  claim  that,  apart  from  the  idea,  an  object  is  "  at 
once  everything  or  nothing."  Further,  Locke  insisted  upon  the 
ultimate  character  of  the  Self  and  its  unavoidable  implication  in 
all  such  determination ;  and,  further,  insisted  upon  a  radical  differ- 
ence in  its  constitution  with  different  men.  Not  only  was  the  Self 
held  as  involved  in  the  production  of  the  secondary  qualities,  which, 
under  a  conceived  difference  in  its  constitution  or  structure,  accord- 
ing to  Locke,  are  bound  to  reveal  things  very  differently,  but  our 
complex  ideas,  whether  substances  or  modes  or  relations,  were 
held  as  further  dependent  in  their  formation,  not  only  "  upon  the 
minds  of  men/7  but  "  upon  the  minds  of  men  variously  collecting 
them."  Every  man,  then,  the  measure  of  his  own  truth !  "  Our 
business  is  living  " ;  our  needs  are  ultimates ;  "  our  faculties  are 
suited  to  our  state  " ;  "  men  determine  sorts  "  and  determine  them 
variously; — here  we  have  fundamental  tenets  in  Locke,  and,  taken 
together,  spell  relativity  of  the  Protagorean  type. 

On  the  other  hand,  Locke  strongly  emphasizes  the  fact  that  in 
Nature  we  find  a  common  standard  of  reference ;  speaks  of  "  unal- 
terable organs";  and  speaks  of  certain  common  ends, — language, 
duty,  common  affairs,  and  whatnot,  and  that  such  principles  make 
for  identity  in  our  perceptions  and  not  for  diversity.  But  even 
within  the  range  of  a  common  knowledge,  Locke's  emphasis  is  upon 
individual  diversity,  and,  secondly,  upon  the  fact  that  human 
knowledge  as  human  knowledge,  is  relative  to  its  own  peculiar 
constitution  and  bias,  be  that  what  it  will.  To  speak,  then,  of  an 
absolute  knowledge  in  the  sense  of  a  knowledge  that  is  inherently 
non-relative,  is  a  wild  and  wholly  groundless  assumption  from  the 
Lockean  standpoint;  and,  further,  to  speak  within  the  limits  of 
our  possible  knowledge,  of  a  knowledge  that  is  absolutely  common 
to  all,  is  equally  wild  and  groundless.  Individual  differences 

87 


88 

exist;  they  are  ultimate;  and  they  are  no  more  to  be  crowded  out 
than  our  identity  with  others,  in  so  far  as  we  are  identical,  is  to  be 
eliminated.  We  see  as  we  are  conditioned  to  see,  be  the  conditions 
for  likeness  or  difference  of  perception  wliat  it  will;  and  if,  in  the 
former  case,  no  man  can  get  away  from  his  Self  or  outside  of  his 
skin  to  see  things  face  to  face,  as  it  were,  even  where  a  relative 
independence  in  the  structure  of  objects  be  granted;  so  in  the 
other  case,  no  man  can  crawl  wholly  within  the  skin  of  another 
man  and  see  things  just  as  he  is  absolutely  conditioned,  within  his 
ultimate  difference,  in  seeing  them. 

Does  this  spell  scepticism?  Xo;  not  any  more  so  than  it  can 
be  made  to  spell  phenomenalism.  Failure  to  perceive  this  truth 
lies  in  our  failure  properly  to  conceive  and  apply  the  principle  of 
relativity.  Let  me  enlarge  upon  this  point,  but,  first  of  all,  I  beg 
to  premise,  what  will  be  granted  without  dispute,  that  a  truth's 
validity  lies  in  its  finality  or  necessity,  be  our  ground  or  criterion 
what  it  will. 

Every  man  inhabits  a  world  of  his  own  and  the  tongue  he 
speaks  is  not  always  the  tongue  others  speak.  Untrained  in  music, 
how  can  I  begin  to  picture  that  world,  in  all  its  serious  interest, 
beauty,  and  significance  in  which  Beethoven,  Wagner,  or  a  Handel 
really  lived,  moved,  and  had  their  being  ?  Unless  I  have  intimately 
felt  the  heart-throb  of  Nature  as  a  Wordsworth  felt  it,  can  I  really 
understand  and  appreciate  half  that  Wordsworth  writes  and  talks 
about?  Is  not  a  Dante's  world,  or  a  Bismarck's  world,  or  even  a 
humble  peasant's  world,  worlds  baffling  any  proper  sort  of  under- 
standing save  in  each  case  through  some  honest  effort  at  identity 
of  consciousness  with  them?  Keeping  this  truth  in  mind,  we  are 
in  a  position  to  appraise  that  very  general  conviction  among 
artists  that  men  have  eyes,  yet  see  not ;  among  musicians,  that  men 
have  ears,  yet  hear  not;  among  poets,  that  men  have  hearts,  yet 
feel  not ;  and  among  thinkers,  that  men  have  brains,  yet  think  not. 
They  forget  that  each  of  us  and  each  of  them  has  his  special  and 
conditioned  range  of  vision,  and,  in  consequence,  his  particular 
world,  and  that  we,  in  each  case,  may  be  using  all  our  faculties 
to  their  fullest,  even  though  we  use  them  differently.  Thus  for  an 
artist,  as  indicated  above,  there  is  no  object  in  nature  but  has  its 
constantly  shifting  and  varying  moods,  tints,  forms,  expression, 
light  and  shade,  and  herein  alone,  he  holds,  do  you  get  an  object's 
particular  soul  and  pulse.  He  sees  a  thousand  shades  and  tints 
where  we  see  none.  Hence  we  go  reputed  as  blind.  But  even  if 
the  botanist  fails  to  note  this  rich  play  of  light  and  shade,  has  the 


89 

artist  necessarily  on  the  other  hand  the  botanist's  keen  and  sharp 
perception  for  plant  structure,  or  the  physician's  keen  and  sharp 
perception  for  the  most  evanescent  symptom  of  disease?  And 
when  you  complicate  the  situation  by  the  addition  in  each  case  of 
interests,  aims,  standards,  and  conditions  more  or  less  unique 
with  the  general  world  of  each,  and  with  each  individual  in  par- 
ticular, where  in  this  state  of  affairs  is  one  man  likely  to  find 
the  other? 

But  it  may  be  argued  that  the  difference  in  each  case  is  nothing 
compared  to  what  is  held  in  common.  If  the  world  of  the  artist, 
in  its  difference,  did  not  constitute  the  main  world  with  him,  why 
does  his  world  so  completely  fill  his  space,  that,  not  to  exercise  our 
eyes  and  faculties  as  he  does,  however  much  we  exercise  them  dif- 
ferently, is  nevertheless  by  him  viewed  as  not  using  them  at  all. 
"  The  little  more  to  him,  and  how  much  that  is ;  the  little  less,  and 
what  worlds  between ! "  One  man  stands  by  an  accepted  fact  or 
truth,  and  ready  to  bleed  for  it,  which  another  mocks,  but  mocks 
for  the  reason  that  he,  in  turn,  consciously  or  unconsciously,  stands 
by  some  other  accepted  fact  or  truth  which  the  former  man  may 
scorn.  Professor  James,  within  our  own  times,  has  rendered  this 
order  of  experience  an  emphasis  which  demands  a  recognition  even 
larger  than  has  yet  been  accorded  to  it.  Yet  I  turn  to  Robert 
Browning,  the  arch-relativist,  for  its  most  persistent  and  trenchant 
formulation : 

"  What  doos  it  all  menu,  poet  ?    Well, 
Your  brains  beat  into  rhythm — you  tell 
What  we  felt  only;  you  expressed 
Your  bold  things  beautiful  the  best, 
And  face  them  in  rhyme  so,  side  by  side. 
'Tis     something,    nay,    'tis    much — but    then, 
Have  you  yourself  what's  best  for  men? 
Are  you — poor,  sick,  old  ere  your  time — 
Xearer  one  whit  your  own  sublime 
Than    we    who    never   have    turned    a   rhyme? 
Sing,  riding's  a  joy !    For  me,  I  ride. 

"  And  you,  great  sculptor — so,  you  gave 
A  score  of  years  to  Art,  her  slave, 
And  that's  your  Venus — whence  we  turn 
To  yonder  girl  that  fords  the  burn ! 
You  acquiesce  and  shall  I  repine  ? 
What,  man  of  music,  you  grown  gray 
With  notes  and  nothing  else  to  say; 


90 


Is  this  your  sole  praise  from  a  friend, 
"  Greatly  his  opera's  strains  intend, 
But  in  music  we  know  how  fashions  end ! " 
I  gave  my  youth — but  we  ride,  in  fine. 

"  Who  knows  what's  fit  for  us  ? 


What  if  Heaven  be,  that,  fair  and  strong 
At  life's  best,  with  our  eyes  upturned 
Whither  life's  flower  was  first  discerned, 
We,  fixed  so,  ever  should  so  abide  ?  " 


Here,  then,  we  have  what  is  "  final  or  necessary  "  divergently 
affirmed  in  the  experience  of  different  men,  and,  yet,  in  each 
instance,  affirmed  with  a  finality  that  appears  most  ultimate.  But 
with  "  our  business  living  " ;  "  our  needs  ultimate  " ;  "  our  faculties 
suited  to  our  state  " ; — how  can  divergency  in  our  views,  in  so  far 
as  they  are  fundamentally  divergent,  come  to  spell  scepticism,  and 
concord  in  our  views,  in  so  far  as  they  are  conditioned  to  be  in 
concord,  the  opposite?  I  fail  to  see  the  logic  of  such  a  contention, 
as  I  also  fail  to  see  the  logic  of  a  view  of  reality  that  would  claim 
to  know  it  as  if  the  pscho-physical  self,  with  all  its  varied  needs, 
hopes,  aspirations,  defeats,  sense  of  life,  were  not  directly  involved 
in  its  constitution,  and,  from  a  relativistic  standpoint,  varying  in 
their  significance,  like  things  in  general,  from  much  to  little  or 
from  little  to  much.  "  God  has  made  the  intellectual  world  har- 
monious and  beautiful  without  us,"  writes  Locke',  "  but  it  will  never 
come  into  our  heads  all  at  once ;  we  must  bring  it  home  piecemeal, 
and  there  set  it  up  by  our  own  industry,  or  else  we  shall  have  noth- 
ing but  darkness  and  chaos  within,  whatever  order  and  light  be  in 
things  without  us."  1  How  it  is  "  brought  home  piecemeal "  in 
Locke's  account  of  it,  I  have  now,  I  think,  sufficiently  stated  in  our 
extended  study  of  him.  I  turn  therefore  to  the  remaining  point. 

It  was  further  stated  that  relativity  does  not  culminate  in  phe- 
nomenalism, not  any  more  so  than  it  was  found  to  culminate  in 
scepticism.  This  claim  demands  a  word. 

Relativity,  we  affirmed,  implies  the  principle  that  an  object 
reveals  itself  differently  in  different  situations.  Now,  by  placing 
the  psycho-physical  organism,  as  Locke  does,  within  the  system  of 
objects  taken  as  a  whole,  with  its  principles  of  determination  no 

1.  Conduct  of  the  Understanding,  sec.  38.     Italics  mine. 


91 

less  final  and  ultimate  in  character  than  such  principles  as  revealed 
in  objects  at  large,  then  the  principle  of  relative  independence  and 
dependence,  as  already  formulated,  comes  to  hold  no  less  true  of 
given  situations  wherein  the  Self  figures  as  a  part,  than  we  are 
led  to  believe  would  hold  of  objects  in  general.  A  Ding  an  sich,  and 
hence,  phenomenalism,  really  has  no  meaning  at  all  from  a  rela- 
tivistic  standpoint;  a  thing  is  what  it  reveals  itself  to  be  in  any 
given  situation,  or,  by  a  process  of  construction,  is  what  it  was  found 
to  be  in  a  series  of  situations,  which  "  exceed  far  not  only  what  we 
know  but  what  we  are  apt  to  imagine  " ;  and  it  logically  remains 
entirely  beside  the  issue  whether  a  Self  constitutes  a  part  of  each 
such  situation  or  whether  other  objects  do.  Objects  do  not  exist  in 
nature  with  "  prefixed  bounds,"  nor  is  one  boundary  of  them  more 
true  in  the  abstract  than  another,  whether  we  proceed  by  way  of 
analysis  to  a  pale  and  vapid  '  quale/  or,  by  way  of  a  synthesis, 
advance  to  the  Absolute  of  our  objective  idealists.  Whatever  works 
from  a  given  standpoint,  or  within  a  given  situation  or  series  of 
situations,  analyzed  and  synthesized  or  unanalyzed  and  unsyn- 
thesized,  as  the  case  may  be,  is  real.  Hence,  if  valid  from  one  point 
of  view  to  turn  to  a  sensationalism  or  to  some  "  quale  "  for  truth  or 
the  real,  no  viewpoint  could  be  more  astray  if  such  pale  and  ghostly 
types  are  offered  as  samples  of  "  immediacy  "  in  general.  Analysis 
carried  to  the  nth  degree  is  still  analysis  carried  out  to  a  degree, 
and  except  from  some  restricted  aim  or  other,  no  more  capable  of 
uncovering  the  reals  than  synthesis  carried  to  the  Absolute  is  a 
thing  necessary  in  order  to  conceive  them.  Our  reality,  at  whatever 
point  we  may  grapple  with  it  or  break  off  with  it,  is,  in  principle, 
still  complex — it  is  the  postulate  of  all  scientific  inquiry  thus  to 
conceive  the  matter.  On  the  other  hand,  reality  never  reveals  itself 
except  in  a  more  or  less  circumscribed  situation,  or  in  a  series  of 
them  held  together  in  an  idea.  Hence  the  violinist,  in  seeking  what 
he  calls  a  "  tone,"  does  not  turn  to  abstract  analysis  nor  to  an  Abso- 
lute, but  to  his  instrument,  held  intact,  and  of  a  complex  situation 
of  which  he  too  forms  a  part.  And  when  that  tone,  to  which  he 
dedicates  years  and  his  developed  technique  in  achieving,  is  eventr 
ually  evolved,  then  he  claims  to  have  the  one  supremely  real  and 
beautiful  one  which  the  particular  soul  (circumscribed  context)  of 
his  instrument  seems  to  him  capable  of  producing.  He  seeks  the 
real  by  forging  ahead,  and  when  once  attained,  weaves  his  whole 
subsequent  network  of  tones  with  that  one  as  its  ultimate  ground 
or  basis.  And  his  experience  is  the  common  experience  whether  we 
turn  to  srioiu-o  or  to  life  in  general.  The  stripping-process,  so  com- 


92 

mon  in  our  current  search  and  definitions  of  Immediacy  of  Experi- 
ence, is  either  a  search  for  a  non-relative  real,  or  for  a  relative  real 
at  its  protoplasmic  stage  (which  even  at  this  stage,  Heaven  knows 
how  complex  it  may  be) .  It  would  be  like  the  violinist  abandoning 
instruments  entirely  for  getting  a  tone,  or,  in  the  other  case,  aban- 
doning the  violin,  let  us  saj,  for  a  Jew's-harp.  In  either  event, 
what  bearing  has  such  search  in  the  world  of  art,  or  in  any  present 
metaphysical  effort  to  determine  an  object?  There  is  the  tree 
before  me.  What  is  its  total  reality  or  meaning  for  me  ?  Is  yours 
likely  to  be  mine,  or  mine  yours  ?  That,  says  Locke,  depends  upon 
our  complex  ideas  of  it  variously  formed  under  varying  and  very 
complex  conditions.  Science  would  yield  the  fullest  account  of  it 
no  doubt,  and  yet  the  artist's  view  of  it  need  not  be  primarily  the 
view  of  the  scientist,  not  any  more  so  than  the  psychologist's  view 
of  it  need  be  that  of  a  botanist.  Such  I  consider  to  be  Locke's 
philosophy,  and  the  reductio  ad  absurdum  of  his  own  sensational- 
istic  premises ! 

Adhering,  then,  to  the  current  terminology,  we  may  conclude  in 
saying :  whatever  works  is  real ;  merely  adding  thereto :  whatever 
works  in  an  articulated  world  of  recognized  and  established  values; 
a  world  where  Mill's  methods,  so  to  speak,  are  found  efficient  in 
producing  results,  and  where  art,  morality  and  refinement,  in  the 
direction  given  to  them,  are  the  accepted  directions  of  still  larger 
growths  and  results.  Let  any  one  reverse  such  general  order  and 
direction  if  he  chose.  But  if  he  does  so  with  the  hope  of  getting 
something  intrinsically  more  absolute,  he  pursues,  he  knows  not 
what — a  shadow.  Whatever  works,  is  real;  whatever  works  in  the 
fully  articulated  world  of  generally  accepted  science  and  values,,  in 
its  highly  diversified  and  elaborated  directions  of  interest  and  activ- 
ities, and  not  merely  what  works,  as  this  term  what  tvorks  gets  itself 
so  narrowly  or  so  loosely  and  vaguely  defined  in  our  modern  use 
of  it. 


93 


VITA 

The  author  of  the  dissertation,  Henry  Gottlieb  Hartmann,  was 
born  at  Woodhaven,  New  York.  After  the  usual  elementary  and 
the  usual  high  school  course,  the  latter  pursued  at  Polytechnic 
Preparatory  School,  Brooklyn,  X.  Y.,  he  entered  Polytechnic  Insti- 
tute of  Brooklyn,  and  four  years  later,  in  1900,  graduated  from  the 
institution  with,  a  B.A.  degree.  During  the  years  1900-02  he  taught 
English  and  mathematics  at  the  Polytechnic  Preparatory  School, 
and  from  100-3  to  1907  taught  mathematics  at  Cooper  Union,  New 
York  City.  He  did  graduate  work  at  Columbia  University,  1902- 
06  and  1910-11,  pursuing  Philosophy  under  Professors  Woodbridge, 
Dewey,  Fullerton,  Adler,  Montague  and  Jones;  Psychology,  under 
Professors  Cattell  and  Strong;  Economics,  under  Professors  Clark 
and  Seligman ;  and  Education,  under  Professor  MacVannel.  From 
1905  to  1907,  he  lectured  in  Philosophy  at  Polytechnic  Institute, 
Brooklyn.  During  1907,  he  pursued  studies  under  Professors 
Eucken,  Liebmann,  Rein  and  Dinger  at  Jena  University,  Ger- 
many. During  1908-10  he  was  professor  of  Philosophy,  Psychology 
and  Education  at  Acaclia  I' Diversity,  Canada.  Ee-entered  Columbia 
University  ns  a  student  in  1(.)1(),  and  in  the  autumn  of  1911,  he 
became  lecturer  in  Philosophy  at  Columbia  Universit}*. 


14  DAY  USE 

RETURN  TO  DESK  FROM  WHICH  BORROWED 


LOAN  DEPT. 


RENEWALS  ONLY—TEL.  NO.  642-3405 

This  book  is  due  on  the  last  date  stamped  below,  or 
on  the  date  to  which  renewed. 
Renewed  books  are  subject  to  immediate  recall. 

,  _.  , 

I  j*  *»   **     *  -i  8  \ 

IClf  (il) 

IT  

^ 

REC'D  UO 

WY28  '69  -2PM 

LD  21A-40m-2,'69 
(J6057slO)476— A-32 


General  Library 

University  of  California 

Berkeley