Skip to main content

Full text of "The mathematical analysis of logic : being an essay towards a calculus of deductive reasoning"

See other formats


The  Mathematical 
Analysis  of  Logic 

By  GEORGE  BOOLE 


I.I 


NIVER51TY  OF  TORONTO 


UNiV 


OF  TORONTO  ^ 


THE  MATHEMATICAL 
ANALYSIS    OF    LOGIC 


THE  MATHEMATICAL 
ANALYSIS  OF  LOGIC 


BEING   AN  ESSAY   TOWARDS  A 

CALCULUS  OF  DEDUCTIVE 

REASONING 


By    GEORGE    BOOLE 


PHILOSOPHICAL    LIBRARY 
NEW   YORK 


Published  in  the  United  States  of  America 

1948,  by  the   Philosophical  Library,    Inc., 

15  East  40th  Street,  New  York,  N.Y. 


THE  MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS 


OF   LOGIC, 


BEING   AN   ESSAY   TOWARDS  A   CALCULUS 
OF    DEDUCTIVE   REASONING. 


BY    GEORGE  BOOLE. 


' ETTIKOIIHOVOVO-I  fit  Trdcrai   at  tiriffTiJimaL    a\XtjX.<m    Kara   ra    Koivd.       Koivd 
\tyai,    otv   xpiavrai.   ws  IK  TOVTWV    diro&tiKvvvrt?'    ctXX'  ou    irtpl    tov    btiKVvovff 
ou&f.   o  ctiKVvovcri. 

ARISTOTLE,  Anal.  Posf.,  lib.  i.  cap.  xi. 


CAMBRIDGE  : 

MACMILLAN,   BARCLAY,  &  MACMILLAN ; 
LONDON:    GEORGE  BELL. 

1847 


o  / 


PRINTED    IN    ENGLAND   BY 

HENDERSON     &    SPALDING 

LONDON.    W.I 


PREFACE. 


IN  presenting  this  Work  to  public  notice,  I  deem  it  not 
irrelevant  to  observe,  that  speculations  similar  to  those  which 
it  records  have,  at  different  periods,  occupied  my  thoughts. 
In  the  spring  of  the  present  year  my  attention  was  directed 
to  the  question  then  moved  between  Sir  W.  Hamilton  and 
Professor  De  Morgan;  and  I  was  induced  by  the  interest 
which  it  inspired,  to  resume  the  almost-forgotten  thread  of 
former  inquiries.  It  appeared  to  me  that,  although  Logic 
might  be  viewed  with  reference  to  the  idea  of  quantity,*  it 
had  also  another  and  a  deeper  system  of  relations.  If  it  was 
lawful  to  regard  it  from  without,  as  connecting  itself  through 
the  medium  of  Number  with  the  intuitions  of  Space  and  Time, 
it  was  lawful  also  to  regard  it  from  within,  as  based  upon 
facts  of  another  order  which  have  their  abode  in  the  consti 
tution  of  the  Mind.  The  results  of  this  view,  and  of  the 
inquiries  which  it  suggested,  are  embodied,  in  the  following 
Treatise. 

It  is  not  generally  permitted  to  an  Author  to  prescribe 
the  mode  in  which  his  production  shall  be  judged ;  but  there 
are  two  conditions  which  I  may  venture  to  require  of  those 
who  shall  undertake  to  estimate  the  merits  of  this  performance. 
The  first  is,  that  no  preconceived  notion  of  the  impossibility 
of  its  objects  shall  be  permitted  to  interfere  with  that  candour 
and  impartiality  which  the  investigation  of  Truth  demands ; 
the  second  is,  that  their  judgment  of  the  system  as  a  whole 
shall  not  be  founded  either  upon  the  examination  of  only 

*  See  p.  42. 


PREFACE. 

a  part  of  it,  or  upon  the  measure  of  its  conformity  with  any 
received  system,  considered  as  a  standard  of  reference  from 
which  appeal  is  denied.  It  is  in  the  general  theorems  which 
occupy  the  latter  chapters  of  this  work, — results  to  which  there 
is  no  existing  counterpart, — that  the  claims  of  the  method,  as 
a  Calculus  of  Deductive  Reasoning,  are  most  fully  set  forth. 

What  may  be  the  final  estimate  of  the  value  of  the  system, 
I  have  neither  the  wish  nor  the  right  to  anticipate.  The 
estimation  of  a  theory  is  not  simply  determined  by  its  truth 
It  also  depends  upon  the  importance  of  its  subject,  and  the 
extent  of  its  applications;  beyond  which  something  must  still 
be  left  to  the  arbitrariness  of  human  Opinion.  If  the  utility 
of  the  application  of  Mathematical  forms  to  the  science  of 
Logic  were  solely  a  question  of  Notation,  I  should  be  content 
to  rest  the  defence  of  this  attempt  upon  a  principle  which  has 
been  stated  by  an  able  living  writer :  "  Whenever  the  nature 
of  the  subject  permits  the  reasoning  process  to  be  without 
danger  carried  on  mechanically,  the  language  should  be  con 
structed  on  as  mechanical  principles  as  possible ;  while  in  the 
contrary  case  it  should  be  so  constructed,  that  there  shall  be 
the  greatest  possible  obstacle  to  a  mere  mechanical  use  of  it."* 
In  one  respect,  the  science  of  Logic  differs  from  all  others; 
the  perfection  of  its  method  is  chiefly  valuable  as  an  evidence 
of  the  speculative  truth  of  its  principles.  To  supersede  the 
employment  of  common  reason,  or  to  subject  it  to  the  rigour 
of  technical  forms,  would  be  the  last  desire  of  one  who  knows 
the  value  of  that  intellectual  toil  and  warfare  which  imparts 
to  the  mind  an  athletic  vigour,  and  teaches  it  to  contend 
with  difficulties  and  to  rely  upon  itself  in  emergencies. 

*  Mill's  System  of  Logic,  Ratiocinative  and  Inductive,  Vol.  II.  p.  292. 
LINCOLN,   Oct.  29,  1847. 


MATHEMATICAL  ANALYSIS   OF   LOGIC. 


INTRODUCTION. 

THEY  who  are  acquainted  with  the  present  state  of  the  theory 
of  Symbolical  Algebra,  are  aware,  that  the  validity  of  the 
processes  of  analysis  does  not  depend  upon  the  interpretation 
of  the  symbols  which  are  employed,  but  solely  upon  the  laws 
of  their  combination.  Every  system  of  interpretation  which 
does  not  affect  the  truth  of  the  relations  supposed,  is  equally 
admissible,  and  it  is  thus  that  the  same  process  may,  under 
one  scheme  of  interpretation,  represent  the  solution  of  a  ques 
tion  on  the  properties  of  numbers,  under  another,  that  of 
a  geometrical  problem,  and  under  a  third,  that  of  a  problem 
of  dynamics  or  optics.  This  principle  is  indeed  of  fundamental 
importance ;  and  it  may  with  safety  be  affirmed,  that  the  recent 
advances  of  pure  analysis  have  been  much  assisted  by  the 
influence  which  it  has  exerted  in  directing  the  current  of 
investigation. 

But  the  full  recognition  of  the  consequences  of  this  important 
doctrine  has  been,  in  some  measure,  retarded  by  accidental 
circumstances.  It  has  happened  in  every  known  form  of 
analysis,  that  the  elements  to  be  determined  have  been  con 
ceived  as  measurable  by  comparison  with  some  fixed  standard. 
The  predominant  idea  has  been  that  of  magnitude,  or  more 
strictly,  of  numerical  ratio.  The  expression  of  magnitude,  or 

B 


4  INTRODUCTION. 

of  operations  upon  magnitude,  has  been  -the  express  object 
for  which  the  symbols  of  Analysis  have  been  invented,  and 
for  which  their  laws  have  been  investigated.  Thus  the  ab 
stractions  of  the  modern  Analysis,  not  less  than  the  ostensive 
diagrams  of  the  ancient  Geometry,  have  encouraged  the  notion, 
that  Mathematics  are  essentially,  as  well  as  actually,  the  Science 
of  Magnitude. 

The  consideration  of  that  view  which  has  already  been  stated, 
as  embodying  the  true  principle  of  the  Algebra  of  Symbols, 
would,  however,  lead  us  to  infer  that  this  conclusion  is  by  no 
means  necessary.  If  every  existing  interpretation  is  shewn  to 
involve  the  idea  of  magnitude,  it  is  only  by  induction  that  we 
can  assert  that  no  other  interpretation  is  possible.  And  it  may 
be  doubted  whether  our  experience  is  sufficient  to  render  such 
an  induction  legitimate.  The  history  of  pure  Analysis  is,  it  may 
be  said,  too  recent  to  permit  us  to  set  limits  to  the  extent  of  its 
applications.  Should  we  grant  to  the  inference  a  high  degree 
of  probability,  we  might  still,  and  with  reason,  maintain  the 
sufficiency  of  the  definition  to  which  the  principle  already  stated 
would  lead  us.  We  might  justly  assign  it  as  the  definitive 
character  of  a  true  Calculus,  that  it  is  a  method  resting  upon 
the  employment  of  Symbols,  whose  laws  of  combination  are 
known  and  general,  and  whose  results  admit  of  a  consistent 
interpretation.  That  to  the  existing  forms  of  Analysis  a  quan 
titative  interpretation  is  assigned,  is  the  result  of  the  circum 
stances  by  which  those  forms  were  determined,  and  is  not  to 
be  construed  into  a  universal  condition  of  Analysis.  It  is  upon 
the  foundation  of  this  general  principle,  that  I  purpose  to 
establish  the  Calculus  of  Logic,  and  that  I  claim  for  it  a  place 
among  the  acknowledged  forms  of  Mathematical  Analysis,  re 
gardless  that  in  its  object  and  in  its  instruments  it  must  at 
present  stand  alone. 

That  which  renders  Logic  possible,  is  the  existence  in  our 
minds  of  general  notions, — our  ability  to  conceive  of  a  class, 
and  to  designate  its  individual  members  by  a  common  name. 


INTRODUCTION.  O 

The  theory  of  Logic  is  thus  intimately  connected  with  that  of 
Language.  A  successful  attempt  to  express  logical  propositions 
by  symbols,  the  laws  of  whose  combinations  should  be  founded 
upon  the  laws  of  the  mental  processes  which  they  represent, 
would,  so  far,  be  a  step  toward  a  philosophical  language.  But 
this  is  a  view  which  we  need  not  here  follow  into  detail.* 
Assuming  the  notion  of  a  class,  we  are  able,  from  any  con 
ceivable  collection  of  objects,  to  separate  by  a  mental  act,  those 
which  belong  to  the  given  class,  and  to  contemplate  them  apart 
from  the  rest.  Such,  or  a  similar  act  of  election,  we  may  con 
ceive  to  be  repeated.  The  group  of  individuals  left  under  con 
sideration  may  be  still  further  limited,  by  mentally  selecting 
those  among  them  which  belong  to  some  other  recognised  class, 
as  well  as  to  the  one  before  contemplated.  And  this  process 
may  be  repeated  with  other  elements  of  distinction,  until  we 
arrive  at  an  individual  possessing  all  the  distinctive  characters 
which  we  have  taken  into  account,  and  a  member,  at  the  same 
time,  of  every  class  which  we  have  enumerated.  It  is  in  fact 
a  method  similar  to  this  which  we  employ  whenever,  in  common 
language,  we  accumulate  descriptive  epithets  for  the  sake  of 
more  precise  definition. 

Now  the  several  mental  operations  which  in  the  above  case 
we  have  supposed  to  be  performed,  are  subject  to  peculiar  laws. 
It  is  possible  to  assign  relations  among  them,  whether  as  re 
spects  the  repetition  of  a  given  operation  or  the  succession  of 
different  ones,  or  some  other  particular,  which  are  never  violated. 
It  is,  for  example,  true  that  the  result  of  two  successive  acts  is 

*  This  view  is  well  expressed  in  one  of  Blanco  White's  Letters  : — "  Logic  is 
for  the  most  part  a  collection  of  technical  rules  founded  on  classification.  The 
Syllogism  is  nothing  but  a  result  of  the  classification  of  things,  which  the  mind 
naturally  and  necessarily  forms,  in  forming  a  language.  All  abstract  terms  are 
classifications  ;  or  rather  the  labels  of  the  classes  which  the  mind  has  settled." 
— Memoirs  of  the  Rev.  Joseph  Blanco  White,  vol.  n.  p.  163.  See  also,  for  a  very 
lucid  introduction,  Dr.  Latham's  First  Outlines  of  Logic  applied  to  Language^ 
Becker's  German  Grammar,  8$c.  Extreme  Nominalists  make  Logic  entirely 
dependent  upon  language.  For  the  opposite  view,  see  Cudworth's  Eternal 
and  Immutable  Morality,  Book  iv.  Chap.  in. 

JB2 


6  INTRODUCTION. 

unaffected  by  the  order  in  which  they  are  performed  ;  and  there 
are  at  least  two  other  laws  which  will  be  pointed  out  in  the 
proper  place.  These  will  perhaps  to  some  appear  so  obvious  as 
to  be  ranked  among  necessary  truths,  and  so  little  important 
as  to  be  undeserving  of  special  notice.  And  probably  they  are 
noticed  for  the  first  time  in  this  Essay.  Yet  it  may  with  con 
fidence  be  asserted,  that  if  they  were  other  than  they  are,  the 
entire  mechanism  of  reasoning,  nay  the  very  laws  and  constitu 
tion  of  the  human  intellect,  would  be  vitally  changed.  A  Logic 
might  indeed  exist,  but  it  would  no  longer  be  the  Logic  we 
possess. 

Such  are  the  elementary  laws  upon  the  existence  of  which, 
and  upon  their  capability  of  exact  symbolical  expression,  the 
method  of  the  following  Essay  is  founded ;  and  it  is  presumed 
that  the  object  which  it  seeks  to  attain  will  be  thought  to 
have  been  very  fully  accomplished.  Every  logical  proposition, 
whether  categorical  or  hypothetical,  will  be  found  to  be  capable 
of  exact  and  rigorous  expression,  and  not  only  will  the  laws  of 
conversion  and  of  syllogism  be  thence  deducible,  but  the  resolu 
tion  of  the  most  complex  systems  of  propositions,  the  separation 
of  any  proposed  element,  and  the  expression  of  its  value  in 
terms  of  the  remaining  elements,  with  every  subsidiary  rela 
tion  involved.  Every  process  will  represent  deduction,  every 
mathematical  consequence  will  express  a  logical  inference.  The 
generality  of  the  method  will  even  permit  us  to  express  arbi 
trary  operations  of  the  intellect,  and  thus  lead  to  the  demon 
stration  of  general  theorems  in  logic  analogous,  in  no  slight 
degree,  to  the  general  theorems  of  ordinary  mathematics.  No 
inconsiderable  part  of  the  pleasure  which  we  derive  from  the 
application  of  analysis  to  the  interpretation  of  external  nature, 
arises  from  the  conceptions  which  it  enables  us  to  form  of  the 
universality  of  the  dominion  of  law.  The  general  formula  to 
which  we  are  conducted  seem  to  give  to  that  element  a  visible 
presence,  and  the  multitude  of  particular  cases  to  which  they 
apply,  demonstrate  the  extent  of  its  sway.  Even  the  symmetry 


INTRODUCTION.  » 

of  their  analytical  expression  may  in  no  fanciful  sense  be 
deemed  indicative  of  its  harmony  and  its  consistency.  Now  I 
do  not  presume  to  say  to  what  extent  the  same  sources  of 
pleasure  are  opened  in  the  following  Essay.  The  measure  of 
that  extent  may  be  left  to  the  estimate  of  those  who  shall  think 
the  subject  worthy  of  their  study.  But  I  may  venture  to 
assert  that  such  occasions  of  intellectual  gratification  are  not 
here  wanting.  The  laws  we  have  to  examine  are  the  laws  of 
one  of  the  most  important  of  our  mental  faculties.  The  mathe 
matics  we  have  to  construct  are  the  mathematics  of  the  human 
intellect.  Nor  are  the  form  and  character  of  the  method,  apart 
from  all  regard  to  its  interpretation,  undeserving  of  notice. 
There  is  even  a  remarkable  exemplification,  in  its  general 
theorems,  of  that  species  of  excellence  which  consists  in  free 
dom  from  exception.  -And.  this  is  observed  where,  in  the  cor 
responding  cases  of  the  received  mathematics,  such  a  character 
is  by  no  means  apparent.  The  few  who  think  that  there  is  that 
in  analysis  which  renders  it  deserving  of  attention  for  its  own 
sake,  may  find  it  worth  while  to  study  it  under  a  form  in  which 
every  equation  can  be  solved  and  every  solution  interpreted. 
Nor  will  it  lessen  the  interest  of  this  study  to  reflect  that  every 
peculiarity  which  they  will  notice  in  the  form  of  the  Calculus 
represents  a  corresponding  feature  in  the  constitution  of  their 
own  minds. 

It  would  be  premature  to  speak  of  the  value  which  this 
method  may  possess  as  an  instrument  of  scientific  investigation. 
I  speak  here  with  reference  to  the  theory  of  reasoning,  and  to 
the  principle  of  a  true  classification  of  the  forms  and  cases  of 
Logic  considered  as  a  Science.*  The  aim  of  these  investigations 
was  in  the  first  instance  confined  to  the  expression  of  the 
received  logic,  and  to  the  forms  of  the  Aristotelian  arrangement, 

*  "  Strictly  a  Science" ;  also  "an  Art."—  WJiately's  Elements  of  Logic.  Indeed 
ought  we  not  to  reg.ord  all  Art  as  applied  Science  ;  unless  we  are  willing,  with 
"the  multitude/'  to  consider  Art  as  "guessing  and  aiming  well"  ?— Plato, 
Phikbus. 


INTRODUCTION. 


but  it  soon  became  apparent  that  restrictions  were  thus  intro 
duced,  which  were  purely  arbitrary  and  had  no  foundation  in 
the  nature  of  things.  These  were  noted  as  they  occurred,  and 
will  be  discussed  in  the  proper  place.  When  it  became  neces 
sary  to  consider  the  subject  of  hypothetical  propositions  (in  which 
comparatively  less  has  been  done),  and  still  more,  when  an 
interpretation  was  demanded  for  the  general  theorems  of  the 
Calculus,  it  was  found  to  be  imperative  to  dismiss  all  regard  for 
precedent  and  authority,  and  to  interrogate  the  method  itself  for 
an  expression  of  the  just  limits  of  its  application.  Still,  how 
ever,  there  was  no  special  effort  to  arrive  at  novel  results.  But 
among  those  which  at  the  time  of  their  discovery  appeared  to  be 
such,  it  may  be  proper  to  notice  the  following. 

A  logical  proposition  is,  according  to  the  method  of  this  Essay, 
expressible  by  an  equation  the  form  of  which  determines  the 
rules  of  conversion  and  of  transformation,  to  which  the  given 
proposition  is  subject.  Thus  the  law  of  what  logicians  term 
simple  conversion,  is  determined  by  the  fact,  that  the  corre 
sponding  equations  are  symmetrical,  that  they  are  unaffected  by 
a  mutual  change  of  place,  in  those  symbols  which  correspond 
to  the  convertible  classes.  The  received  laws  of  conversion 
were  thus  determined,  and  afterwards  another  system,  which  is 
thought  to  be  more  elementary,  and  more  general.  See  Chapter, 
On  the  Conversion  of  Propositions. 

The  premises  of  a  syllogism  being  expressed  by  equations,  the 
elimination  of  a  common  symbol  between  them  leads  to  a  third 
equation  which  expresses  the  conclusion,  this  conclusion  being 
always  the  most  general  possible,  whether  Aristotelian  or  not. 
Among  the  cases  in  which  no  inference  was  possible,  it  was 
found,  that  there  were  two  distinct  forms  of  the  final  equation. 
It  was  a  considerable  time  before  the  explanation  of  this  fact 
was  discovered,  but  it  was  at  length  seen  to  depend  upon  the 
presence  or  absence  of  a  true  medium  of  comparison  between 
the  premises.  The  distinction  which  is  thought  to  be  new 
is  illustrated  in  the  Chapter,  On  Syllogisms. 


INTRODUCTION. 

The  nonexclusive  character  of  the  disjunctive  conclusion  of 
a  hypothetical  syllogism,  is  very  clearly  pointed  out  in  the 
examples  of  this  species  of  argument. 

The  class  of  logical  problems  illustrated  in  the  chapter,  On 
the  Solution  of  Elective  Equations ,  is  conceived  to  be  new :  and 
it  is  believed  that  the  method  of  that  chapter  affords  the  means 
of  a  perfect  analysis  of  any  conceivable  system  of  propositions, 
an  end  toward  which  the  rules  for  the  conversion  of  a  single 
categorical  proposition  are  but  the  first  step. 

However,  upon  the  originality  of  these  or  any  of  these  views, 
I  am  conscious  that  I  possess  too  slight  an  acquaintance  with  the 
literature  of  logical  science,  and  especially  with  its  older  lite 
rature,  to  permit  me  to  speak  with  confidence. 

It  may  not  be  inappropriate,  before  concluding  these  obser 
vations,  to  offer  a  few  remarks  upon  the  general  question  of  the 
use  of  symbolical  language  in  the  mathematics.  Objections 
have  lately  been  very  strongly  urged  against  this  practice,  on 
the  ground,  that  by  obviating  the  necessity  of  thought,  and 
substituting  a  reference  to  general  formulae  in  the  room  of 
personal  effort,  it  tends  to  weaken  the  reasoning  faculties. 

Now  the  question  of  the  use  of  symbols  may  be  considered 
in  two  distinct  points  of  view.  First,  it  may  be  considered  with 
reference  to  the  progress  of  scientific  discovery,  and  secondly, 
with  reference  to  its  bearing  upon  the  discipline  of  the  intellect. 

And  with  respect  to  the  first  view,  it  may  be  observed  that 
as  it  is  one  fruit  of  an  accomplished  labour,  that  it  sets  us  at 
liberty  to  engage  in  more  arduous  toils,  so  it  is  a  necessary 
result  of  an  advanced  state  of  science,  that  we  are  permitted, 
and  even  called  upon,  to  proceed  to  higher  problems,  than  those 
which  we  before  contemplated.  The  practical  inference  is 
obvious.  If  through  the  advancing  power  of  scientific  methods, 
we  find  that  the  pursuits  on  which  we  were  once  engaged, 
afford  no  longer  a  sufficiently  ample  field  for  intellectual  effort, 
the  remedy  is,  to  proceed  to  higher  inquiries,  and,  in  new 
tracks,  to  seek  for  difficulties  yet  unsubdued.  And  such  is, 


10 


INTRODUCTION. 


indeed,  the  actual  law  of  scientific  progress.  We  must  be 
content,  either  to  abandon  the  hope  of  further  conquest,  or  to 
employ  such  aids  of  symbolical  language,  as  are  proper  to  the 
stage  of  progress,  at  which  we  have  arrived.  Nor  need  we  fear 
to  commit  ourselves  to  such  a  course.  We  have  not  yet  arrived 
so  near  to  the  boundaries  of  possible  knowledge,  as  to  suggest 
the  apprehension,  that  scope  will  fail  for  the  exercise  of  the 
inventive  faculties. 

In  discussing  the  second,  and  scarcely  less  momentous  ques 
tion  of  the  influence  of  the  use  of  symbols  upon  the  discipline 
of  the  intellect,  an  important  distinction  ought  to  be  made.  It 
is  of  most  material  consequence,  whether  those  symbols  are 
used  with  a  full  understanding  of  their  meaning,  with  a  perfect 
comprehension  of  that  which  renders  their  use  lawful,  and  an 
ability  to  expand  the  abbreviated  forms  of  reasoning  which  they 
induce,  into  their  full  syllogistic  devolopment ;  or  whether  they 
are  mere  unsuggestive  characters,  the  use  of  which  is  suffered 
to  rest  upon  authority. 

The  answer  which  must  be  given  to  the  question  proposed, 
will  differ  according  as  the  one  or  the  other  of  these  suppositions 
is  admitted.  In  the  former  case  an  intellectual  discipline  of  a 
high  order  is  provided,  an  exercise  not  only  of  reason,  but  of 
the  faculty  of  generalization.  In  the  latter  case  there  is  no 
mental  discipline  whatever.  It  were  perhaps  the  best  security 
against  the  danger  of  an  unreasoning  reliance  upon  symbols, 
on  the  one  hand,  and  a  neglect  of  their  just  claims  on  the  other, 
that  each  subject  of  applied  mathematics  should  be  treated  in  the 
spirit  of  the  methods  which  were  known  at  the  time  when  the 
application  was  made,  but  in  the  best  form  which  those  methods 
have  assumed.  The  order  of  attainment  in  the  individual  mind 
would  thus  bear  some  relation  to  the  actual  order  of  scientific 
discovery,  and  the  more  abstract  methods  of  the  higher  analysis 
would  be  offered  to  such  minds  only,  as  were  prepared  to 
receive  them. 

The  relation  in  which  this  Essay  stands  at  once  to  Logic  and 


INTRODUCTION.  11 

to  Mathematics,  may  further  justify  some  notice  of  the  question 
which  has  lately  been  revived,  as  to  the  relative  value  of  the  two 
studies  in  a  liberal  education.  One  of  the  chief  objections  which 
have  been  urged  against  the  study  of  Mathematics  in  general,  is 
but  another  form  of  that  which  has  been  already  considered  with 
respect  to  the  use  of  symbols  in  particular.  And  it  need  not  here 
be  further  dwelt  upon,  than  to  notice,  that  if  it  avails  anything, 
it  applies  with  an  equal  force  against  the  study  of  Logic.  The 
canonical  forms  of  the  Aristotelian  syllogism  are  really  symbol 
ical  ;  only  the  symbols  are  less  perfect  of  their  kind  than  those 
of  mathematics.  If  they  are  employed  to  test  the  validity  of  an 
argument,  they  as  truly  supersede  the  exercise  of  reason,  as  does 
a  reference  to  a  formula  of  analysis.  Whether  men  do,  in  the 
present  day,  make  this  use  of  the  Aristotelian  canons,  except  as 
a  special  illustration  of  the  rules  of  Logic,  may  be  doubted ;  yet 
it  cannot  be  questioned  that  when  the  authority  of  Aristotle  was 
dominant  in  the  schools  of  Europe,  such  applications  were  habit 
ually  made.  And  our  argument  only  requires  the  admission, 
that  the  case  is  possible. 

But  the  question  before  us  has  been  argued  upon  higher 
grounds.  Regarding  Logic  as  a  branch  of  Philosophy,  and  de 
fining  Philosophy  as  the  "science  of  a  real  existence,"  and  "the 
research  of  causes,"  and  assigning  as  its  main  business  the  inves 
tigation  of  the  "  why,  (TO  Slori,),"  while  Mathematics  display 
only  the  "  that,  (TO  oYl),"  Sir  W.  Hamilton  has  contended, 
not  simply,  that  the  superiority  rests  with  the  study  of  Logic, 
but  that  the  study  of  Mathematics  is  at  once  dangerous  and  use 
less.*  The  pursuits  of  the  mathematician  "  have  not  only  not 
trained  him  to  that  acute  scent,  to  that  delicate,  almost  instinc 
tive,  tact  which,  in  the  twilight  of  probability,  the  search  and 
discrimination  of  its  finer  facts  demand;  they  have  gone  to  cloud 
his  vision,  to  indurate  his  touch,  to  all  but  the  blazing  light,  the 
iron  chain  of  demonstration,  and  left  him  out  of  the  narrow  con 
fines  of  his  science,  to  a  passive  credulity  in  any  premises,  or  to 

*  Edinburgh  Review,  vol.  LXII.  p.  409,  and  Letter  to  A.  De  Morgan,  Esq. 


INTRODUCTION. 

an  absolute  incredulity  in  all."  In  support  of  these  and  of  other 
charges,  both  argument  and  copious  authority  are  adduced.* 
I  shall  not  attempt  a  complete  discussion  of  the  topics  which 
are  suggested  by  these  remarks.  My  object  is  not  controversy, 
and  the  observations  which  follow  are  offered  not  in  the  spirit 
of  antagonism,  but  in  the  hope  of  contributing  to  the  formation 
of  just  views  upon  an  important  subject.  Of  Sir  W.  Hamilton 
it  is  impossible  to  speak  otherwise  than  with  that  respect  which 
is  due  to  genius  and  learning. 

Philosophy  is  then  described  as  the  science  of  a  real  existence 
and  the  research  of  causes.  And  that  no  doubt  may  rest  upon 
the  meaning  of  the  word  cause,  it  is  further  said,  that  philosophy 
"  mainly  investigates  the  why."  These  definitions  are  common 
among  the  ancient  writers.  Thus  Seneca,  one  of  Sir  W.  Hamil 
ton's  authorities,  Epistle  LXXXVIIT.,  "  The  philosopher  seeks 
and  knows  the  causes  of  natural  things,  of  which  the  mathe 
matician  searches  out  and  computes  the  numbers  and  the  mea 
sures."  It  may  be  remarked,  in  passing,  that  in  whatever 
degree  the  belief  has  prevailed,  that  the  business  of  philosophy 
is  immediately  with  causes;  in  the  same  degree  has  every 
science  whose  object  is  the  investigation  of  laws,  been  lightly 
esteemed.  Thus  the  Epistle  to  which  we  have  referred,  bestows, 
by  contrast  with  Philosophy,  a  separate  condemnation  on  Music 
and  Grammar,  on  Mathematics  and  Astronomy,  although  it  is 
that  of  Mathematics  only  that  Sir  W.  Hamilton  has  quoted. 

Now  we  might  take  our  stand  upon  the  conviction  of  many 
thoughtful  and  reflective  minds,  that  in  the  extent  of  the  mean 
ing  above  stated,  Philosophy  is  impossible.  The  business  of 
true  Science,  they  conclude,  is  with  laws  and  phenomena.  The 
nature  of  Being,  the  mode  of  the  operation  of  Cause,  the  why, 

•*  The  arguments  are  in  general  better  than  the  authorities.  Many  writers 
quoted  in  condemnation  of  mathematics  (Aristo,  Seneca,  Jerome,  Augustine, 
Cornelius  Agrippa,  &c.)  have  borne  a  no  less  explicit  testimony  against  other 
sciences,  nor  least  of  all,  against  that  of  logic.  The  treatise  of  the  last  named 
writer  De  Vanitate  Scientiantm,  must  surely  have  been  referred  to  by  mistake. — 
Vide  cap.  en. 


INTRODUCTION.  13 

they  hold  to  be  beyond  the  reach  of  our  intelligence.  But  we 
do  not  require  the  vantage-ground  of  this  position;  nor  is  it 
doubted  that  whether  the  aim  of  Philosophy  is  attainable  or  not, 
the  desire  which  impels  us  to  the  attempt  is  an  instinct  of  our 
higher  nature.  Let  it  be  granted  that  the  problem  which  has 
baffled  the  efforts  of  ages,  is  not  a  hopeless  one;  that  the 
"  science  of  a  real  existence,"  and  "  the  research  of  causes," 
"  that  kernel"  for  which  "  Philosophy  is  still  militant,"  do 
not  transcend  the  limits  of  the  human  intellect.  I  am  then 
compelled  to  assert,  that  according  to  this  view  of  the  nature  of 
Philosophy,  Logic  forms  no  part  of  it.  On  the  principle  of 
a  true  classification,  we  ought  no  longer  to  associate  Logic  and 
Metaphysics,  but  Logic  and  Mathematics. 

Should  any  one  after  what  has  been  said,  entertain  a  doubt 
upon  this  point,  I  must  refer  him  to  the  evidence  which  will  be 
afforded  in  the  following  Essay.  He  will  there  see  Logic  resting 
like  Geometry  upon  axiomatic  truths,  and  its  theorems  con 
structed  upon  that  general  doctrine  of  symbols,  which  consti 
tutes  the  foundation  of  the  recognised  Analysis.  In  the  Logic 
of  Aristotle  he  will  be  led  to  view  a  collection  of  the  formulae 
of  the  science,  expressed  by  another,  but,  (it  is  thought)  less 
perfect  scheme  of  symbols.  I  feel  bound  to  contend  for  the 
absolute  exactness  of  this  parallel.  It  is  no  escape  from  the  con 
clusion  to  which  it  points  to  assert,  that  Logic  not  only  constructs 
a  science,  but  also  inquires  into  the  origin  and  the  nature  of  its 
own  principles, — a  distinction  which  is  denied  to  Mathematics. 
"  It  is  wholly  beyond  the  domain  of  mathematicians,"  it  is  said, 
"  to  inquire  into  the  origin  and  nature  of  their  principles." — 
Review,  page  415.  But  upon  what  ground  can  such  a  distinc 
tion  be  maintained  ?  What  definition  of  the  term  Science  will 
be  found  sufficiently  arbitrary  to  allow  such  differences  ? 

The  application  of  this  conclusion  to  the  question  before  us  is 
clear  and  decisive.  The  mental  discipline  which  is  afforded  by 
the  study  of  Logic,  as  an  exact  science,  is,  in  species,  the  same 
as  that  afforded  by  the  study  of  Analysis. 


14  INTRODUCTION. 

Is  it  then  contended  that  either  Logic  or  Mathematics  can 
supply  a  perfect  discipline  to  the  Intellect  ?  The  most  careful 
and  unprejudiced  examination  of  this  question  leads  me  to  doubt 
whether  such  a  position  can  be  maintained.  The  exclusive  claims 
of  either  must,  I  believe,  be  abandoned,  nor  can  any  others,  par 
taking  of  a  like  exclusive  character,  be  admitted  in  their  room. 
It  is  an  important  observation,  which  has  more  than  once  been 
made,  that  it  is  one  thing  to  arrive  at  correct  premises,  and  another 
thing  to  deduce  logical  conclusions,  and  that  the  business  of  life 
depends  more  upon  the  former  than  upon  the  latter.  The  study 
of  the  exact  sciences  may  teach  us  the  one,  and  it  may  give  us 
some  general  preparation  of  knowledge  and  of  practice  for  the 
attainment  of  the  other,  but  it  is  to  the  union  of  thought  with 
action,  in  the  field  of  Practical  Logic,  the  arena  of  Human  Life, 
that  we  are  to  look  for  its  fuller  and  more  perfect  accomplishment. 

I  desire  here  to  express  my  conviction,  that  with  the  ad 
vance  of  our  knowledge  of  all  true  science,  an  ever-increasing 
harmony  will  be  found  to  prevail  among  its  separate  branches. 
The  view  winch  leads  to  the  rejection  of  one,  ought,  if  con 
sistent,  to  lead  to  the  rejection  of  others.  And  indeed  many 
of  the  authorities  which  have  been  quoted  against  the  study 
of  Mathematics,  are  even  more  explicit  in  their  condemnation  of 
Logic.  "  Natural  science,"  says  the  Chian  Aristo,  "  is  above  us, 
Logical  science  does  not  concern  us."  When  such  conclusions 
are  founded  (as  they  often  are)  upon  a  deep  conviction  of  the 
preeminent  value  and  importance  of  the  study  of  Morals,  we 
admit  the  premises,  but  must  demur  to  the  inference.  For  it 
has  been  well  said  by  an  ancient  writer,  that  it  is  the  "  charac 
teristic  of  the  liberal  sciences,  not  that  they  conduct  us  to  Virtue, 
but  that  they  prepare  us  for  Virtue ;"  and  Melancthon's  senti 
ment,  "  abeunt  studia  in  mores,"  has  passed  into  a  proverb. 
Moreover,  there  is  a  common  ground  upon  which  all  sincere 
votaries  of  truth  may  meet,  exchanging  with  each  other  the 
language  of  Flamsteed's  appeal  to  Newton,  "  The  works  of  the 
Eternal  Providence  will  be  better  understood  through  your 
labors  and  mine." 


(     15     ) 


FIRST  PRINCIPLES. 


LET  us  employ  the  symbol  1,  or  unity,  to  represent  the 
Universe,  and  let  us  understand  it  as  comprehending  every 
conceivable  class  of  objects  whether  actually  existing  or  not, 
it  being  premised  that  the  same  individual  may  be  found  in 
more  than  one  class,  inasmuch  as  it  may  possess  more  than  one 
quality  in  common  with  other  individuals.  Let  us  employ  the 
letters  X,  Y,  Z,  to  represent  the  individual  members  of  classes, 
X  applying  to  every  member  of  one  class,  as  members  of  that 
particular  class,  and  Y  to  every  member  of  another  class  as 
members  of  such  class,  and  so  on,  according  to  the  received  lan 
guage  of  treatises  on  Logic. 

Further  let  us  conceive  a  class  of  symbols  x,  y,  z,  possessed 
of  the  following  character. 

The  symbol  x  operating  upon  any  subject  comprehending 
individuals  or  classes,  shall  be  supposed  to  select  from  that 
subject  all  the  Xs  which  it  contains.  In  like  manner  the  symbol 
y,  operating  upon  any  subject,  shall  be  supposed  to  select  from 
it  all  individuals  of  the  class  Y  which  are  comprised  in  it,  and 
so  on. 

When  no  subject  is  expressed,  we  shall  suppose  1  (the  Uni 
verse)  to  be  the  subject  understood,  so  that  we  shall  have 

x  =  x     (1), 

the  meaning  of  either  term  being  the  selection  from  the  Universe 
of  all  the  Xs  which  it  contains,  and  the  result  of  the  operation 


16  FIRST    PRINCIPLES. 

being  in  common  language,  the  class  X,  i.  e.  the  class  of  which 
each  member  is  an  X. 

From  these  premises  it  will  follow,  that  the  product  xy  will 
represent,  in  succession,  the  selection  of  the  class  Y,  and  the 
selection  from  the  class  Y  of  such  individuals  of  the  class  X  as 
are  contained  in  it,  the  result  being  the  class  whose  members  are 
both  Xs  and  Ys.  And  in  like  manner  the  product  xyz  will 
represent  a  compound  operation  of  which  the  successive  ele 
ments  are  the  selection  of  the  class  Z,  the  selection  from  it  of 
such  individuals  of  the  class  Y  as  are  contained  in  it,  and  the 
selection  from  the  result  thus  obtained  of  all  the  individuals  of 
the  class  X  which  it  contains,  the  final  result  being  the  class 
common  to  X,  Y,  and  Z. 

From  the  nature  of  the  operation  which  the  symbols  x,  y,  'z, 
are  conceived  to  represent,  we  shall  designate  them  as  elective 
symbols.  An  expression  in  which  they  are  involved  will  be 
called  an  elective  function,  and  an  equation  of  which  the  mem 
bers  are  elective  functions,  will  be  termed  an  elective  equation. 

It  will  not  be  necessary  that  we  should  here  enter  into  the 
analysis  of  that  mental  operation  which  we  have  represented  by 
the  elective  symbol.  It  is  not  an  aqt  of  Abstraction  according 
to  the  common  acceptation  of  that  term,  because  we  never  lose 
sight  of  the  concrete,  but  it  may  probably  be  referred  .to  an  ex 
ercise  of  the  faculties  of  Comparison  and  Attention.  Our  present 
concern  is  rather  with  the  laws  of  combination  and  of  succession, 
by  which  its  results  are  governed,  and  of  these  it  will  suffice  to 
notice  the  following. 

1st.  The  result  of  an  act  of  election  is  independent  of  the 
grouping  or  classification  of  the  subject. 

Thus  it  is  indifferent  whether  from  a  group  of  objects  con 
sidered  as  a  whole,  we  select  the  class  X,  or  whether  we  divide 
the  group  into  two  parts,  select  the  Xs  from  them  separately, 
and  then  connect  the  results  in  one  aggregate  conception. 

We  may  express  this  law  mathematically  by  the  equation 
x  (u  +  v)  =  xu  +  xv, 


FIRST     PRINCIPLES.  17 

u  i  v  representing   the  undivided   subject,   and  u  and  v  the 
component  parts  of  it. 

2nd.  It  is  indifferent  in  what  order  two  successive  acts  of 
election  are  performed. 

Whether  from  the  class  of  animals  we  select  sheep,  and  from 
the  sheep  those  which  are  horned,  or  whether  from  the  class  of 
animals  we  select  the  horned,  and  from  these  such  as  are  sheep, 
the  result  is  unaffected.  In  either  case  we  arrive  at  the  class 
horned  sheep. 

The  symbolical  expression  of  this  law  is 

xy  =  yx. 

3rd.  The  result  of  a  given  act  of  election  performed  twice, 
or  any  number  of  times  in  succession,  is  the  result  of  the  same 
act  performed  once. 

If  from  a  group  of  objects  we  select  the  Xs,  we  obtain  a  class 
of  which  all  the  members  are  Xs.  If  we  repeat  the  operation 
on  this  class  no  further  change  will  ensue :  in  selecting  the  Xs 
we  take  the  whole.  Thus  we  have 

xx  =  x, 

or  s*  =  x ; 

and  supposing  the  same  operation  to  be  n  times  performed,  we 
have  xn  =  X) 

which  is  the  mathematical  expression  of  the  law  above  stated.* 
The  laws  we  have  established  under  the  symbolical  forms 

x  (u  +  v)  =  xu  +  xv (1 ), 

xy  =  yx (2), 

*n  =  * (3), 

*  The  office  of  the  elective  symbol  x,  is  to  select  individuals  comprehended 
in  the  class  X.  Let  the  class  X  be  supposed  to  embrace  the  universe ;  then, 
whatever  the  class  Y  may  be,  we  have 

xy  =  y. 

The  office  which  x  performs  is  now  equivalent  to  the  symbol  -f ,  in  one  at 
least  of  its  interpretations,  and  the  index  law  (3)  gives 

+  "  =  +, 
which  is  the  known  property  of  that  symbol. 


18  F1KST    PRINCIPLES. 

are  sufficient  for  the  basis  of  a  Calculus.  From  the  first  of  these, 
it  appears  that  elective  symbols  are  distributive,  from  the  second 
that  they  are  commutative/  properties  which  they  possess  in 
common  with  symbols  of  quantity,  and  in  virtue  of  which,  all 
the  processes  of  common  algebra  are  applicable  to  the  present 
system.  The  one  and  sufficient  axiom  involved  in  this  appli 
cation  is  that  equivalent  operations  performed  upon  equivalent 
subjects  produce  equivalent  results.* 

The  third  law  (3)  we  shall  denominate  the  index  law.  It  is 
peculiar  to  elective  symbols,  and  will  be  found  of  great  impor 
tance  in  enabling  us  to  reduce  our  results  to  forms  meet  for 
interpretation. 

From  the  circumstance  that  the  processes  of  algebra  may  be 
applied  to  the  present  system,  it  is  not  to  be  inferred  that  the 
interpretation  of  an  elective  equation  will  be  unaffected  by  such 
processes.  The  expression  of  a  truth  cannot  be  negatived  by 

*  It  is  generally  asserted  by  writers  on  Logic,  that  all  reasoning  ultimately 
depends  on  an  application  of  the  dictum  of  Aristotle,  de  omni  et  nullo.  "  What 
ever  is  predicated  universally  of  any  class  of  things,  may  be  predicated  in  like 
manner  of  any  thing  comprehended  in  that  class."  But  it  is  agreed  that  this 
dictum  is  not  immediately  applicable  in  all  cases,  and  that  in  a  majority  of 
instances,  a  certain  previous  process  of  reduction  is  necessary.  What  are  the 
elements  involved  in  that  process  of  reduction?  Clearly  they  are  as  much 
a  part  of  general  reasoning  as  the  dictum  itself. 

Another  mode  of  considering  the  subject  resolves  all  reasoning  into  an  appli 
cation  of  one  or  other  of  the  following  canons,  viz. 

1 .  If  two  terms  agree  with  one  and  the  same  third,  they  agree  with  each 
other. 

2.  If  one  term  agrees,  and  another  disagrees,  with  one  and  the  same  third, 
these  two  disagree  with  each  other. 

But  the  application  of  these  canons  depends  on  mental  acts  equivalent  to 
those  which  are  involved  in  the  before-named  process  of  reduction.  We  have  to 
select  individuals  from  classes,  to  convert  propositions,  &c.,  before  we  can  avail 
ourselves  of  their  guidance.  Any  account  of  the  process  of  reasoning  is  insuffi 
cient,  which  does  not  represent,  as  well  the  laws  of  the  operation  which  the 
mind  performs  in  that  process,  as  the  primary  truths  which  it  recognises  and 
applies. 

It  is  presumed  that  the  laws  in  question  are  adequately  represented  by  the 
fundamental  equations  of  the  present  Calculus.  The  proof  of  this  will  be  found 
in  its  capability  of  expressing  propositions,  and  of  exhibiting  in  the  results  of 
its  processes,  every  result  that  may  be  arrived  at  by  ordinary  reasoning. 


FIRST    PRINCIPLES.  19 

a  legitimate  operation,  but  it  may  be  limited.  The  equation 
y  =  z  implies  that  the  classes  Y  and  Z  are  equivalent,  member 
for  member.  Multiply  it  by  a  factor  x,  and  we  have 

xy  =  xz, 

which  expresses  that  the  individuals  which  are  common  to  the 
classes  X  and  Y  are  also  common  to  X  and  Z,  and  vice  versd. 
This  is  a  perfectly  legitimate  inference,  but  the  fact  which  it 
declares  is  a  less  general  one  than  was  asserted  in  the  original 
proposition. 


OF  EXPRESSION   AND   INTERPRETATION. 


A  Proposition  is  a  sentence  which  either  affirms  or  denies,  as,  All  men  are 
mortal,  No  creature  is  independent. 

A  Proposition  has  necessarily  two  terms,  as  men,  mortal;  the  former  of  which, 

'  the  one  spoken  of,  is  called  the  subject ;  the  latter,  or  that  which  is  affirmed 
or  denied  of  the  subject,  the  predicate.  These  are  connected  together  by  the 
copula  is,  or  is  not,  or  by  some  other  modiEcation  of  the  substantive  verb. 

The  substantive  verb  is  the  only  verb  recognised  in  Logic ;  all  others  are 
resolvable  by  means  of  the  verb  to  be  and  a  participle  or  adjective,  e.g.  "  The 
Komans  conquered";  the  word  conquered  is  both  copula  and  predicate,  being 
equivalent  to  "were  (copula)  victorious"  (predicate). 

A  Proposition  must  either  be  affirmative  or  negative,  and  must  be  also  either 
universal  or  particular.  Thus  we  reckon  in  all,  four  kinds  of  pure  categorical 
Propositions. 

1st.  Universal- affirmative,  usually  represented  by  A, 

Ex.     All  Xs  are  Ys. 
2nd.    Universal-negative,  usually  represented  by  E, 

Ex.   NoXsareYs. 
3rd.   Particular-affirmative,  usually  represented  by  I, 

Ex.    Some  Xs  are  Ys. 

4th.   Particular-negative,  usually  represented  by  O,* 
Ex.    Some  Xs  are  not  Ys. 

1.  To  express  the  class,  not-X,  that  is,  the  class  including 
all  individuals  that  are  not  Xs. 

The  class  X  and  the  class  not-X  together  make  the  Universe. 
But  the  Universe  is  1,  and  the  class  X  is  determined  by  the 
symbol  x3  therefore  the  class  not-X  will  be  determined  by 
the  symbol  1  -  x. 

*  The  above  is  taken,  with  little  variation,  from  the  Treatises  of  Aldrich 
and  Whately. 


OF    EXPRESSION    AND    INTERPRETATION. 

Hence  the  office  of  the  symbol  1  -  x  attached  to  a  given 
subject  will  be,  to  select  from  it  all  the  not-Xs  which  it 
contains. 

And  in  like  manner,  as  the  product  xy  expresses  the  entire 
class  whose  members  are  both  Xs  and  Ys,  the  symbol  y  (1  -  x) 
will  represent  the  class  whose  members  are  Ys  but  not  Xs, 
and  the  symbol  (1  -  x)  (1  -  y)  the  entire  class  whose  members 
are  neither  Xs  nor  Ys. 

2.  To  express  the  Proposition,  All  Xs  are  Ys. 

As  all  the  Xs  which  exist  are  found  in  the  class  Y,  it  is 
obvious  that  to  select  out  of  the  Universe  all  Ys,  and  from 
these  to  select  all  Xs,  is  the  same  as  to  select  at  once  from  the 
Universe  all  Xs. 

Hence  xy  =  x, 

or  x  (1  -  y)  =  0,     (4). 

3.  To  express  the  Proposition,  No  Xs  are  Ys. 

To  assert  that  no  Xs  are  Ys,  is  the  same  as  to  assert  that 
there  are  no  terms  common  to  the  classes  X  and  Y.  Now 
all  individuals  common  to  those  classes  are  represented  by  xy. 
Hence  the  Proposition  that  No  Xs  are  Ys,  is  represented  by 

the  equation 

xy  =  0,     (5). 

4.  To  express  the  Proposition,  Some  Xs  are  Ys. 

If  some  Xs  are  Ys,  there  are  some  terms  common  to  the 
classes  X  and  Y.  Let  those  terms  constitute  a  separate  class 
V,  to  which  there  shall  correspond  a  separate  elective  symbol 

v,  then 

v  =  xy,     (6). 

And  as  v  includes  all  terms  common  to  the  classes  X  and  Y, 
we  can  indifferently  interpret  it,  as  Some  Xs,  or  Some  Ys. 

02 


Z  OF    EXPRESSION    AND    INTERPRETATION. 

5.    To  express  the  Proposition,  Some  Xs  are  not  Ys. 
.  In  the  last  equation  write  1  -  y  for  y,  and  we  have 


the  interpretation  of  v  being  indifferently  Some  Xs  or  Some 
not-Ys. 

The  above  equations  involve  the  complete  theory  of  cate 
gorical  Propositions,  and  so  far  as  respects  the  employment  of 
analysis  for  the  deduction  of  logical  inferences,  nothing  more 
can  be  desired.  But  it  may  be  satisfactory  to  notice  some  par 
ticular  forms  deducible  from  the  third  and  fourth  equations,  and 
susceptible  of  similar  application. 

If  we  multiply  the  equation  (6)  by  x,  we  have 

vx  =  x*y  =  xy  by  (3). 
Comparing  with  (6),  we  find 

v  =  tx, 
or  v  (1  -  x)  =  0,     (8). 

And  multiplying  (6)  by  y,  and  reducing  in  a  similar  manner, 

we  have 

v  =  vy, 

or  v  (1  -  y}  =  0,     (9). 

Comparing  (8)  and  (9), 

vx  =  ty  =  v,     (10). 

And  further  comparing  (8)  and  (9)  with  (4),  we  have  as  the 
equivalent  of  this  system  of  equations  the  Propositions 

All  Vs  are  Xs\ 

All  Vs  are  YsJ  ' 

The  system  (10)  might  be  used  to  replace  (6),  or  the  single 

equation 

vx  =  vy,     (11), 

might  be  used,  assigning  to  vx  the  interpretation,  Some  Xs,  and 
to  vy  the  interpretation,  Some  Ys.  But  it  will  be  observed  that 


ON    EXPRESSION    AND    INTERPRETATION.  23 

this  system  does  not  express  quite  so  much  as  the  single  equa 
tion  (6),  from  which  it  is  derived.  Both,  indeed,  express  the 
Proposition,  Some  Xs  are  Ys,  but  the  system  (10)  does  not 
imply  that  the  class  V  includes  all  the  terms  that  are  common 
to  X  and  Y. 

In  like  manner,  from  the  equation  (7)  which  expresses  the 
Proposition  Some  Xs  are  not  Ys,  we  may  deduce  the  system 

ra?  =  c(l  -  y)  =  t>,     (12), 

in  which  the  interpretation  of  v  (1  -  y)  is  Some  not-Ys.  Since 
in  this  case  vy  =  0,  we  must  of  course  be  careful  not  to  in 
terpret  vy  as  Some  Ys. 

If  we  multiply  the  first  equation  of  the  system  (12),  viz. 

ex  -v  (I  -  y), 
by  y,  we  have 

vxy  =  t-y  (1  -  y); 

.-.  vxy  =  0,     (13), 

which  is  a  form  that  will  occasionally  present  itself.  It  is  not 
necessary  to  revert  to  the  primitive  equation  in  order  to  inter 
pret  this,  for  the  condition  that  vx  represents  Some  Xs,  shews 
us  by  virtue  of  (5),  that  its  import  will  be 

Some  Xs  are  not  Ys, 

the  subject  comprising  all  the  Xs  that  are  found  in  the  class  V. 

Universally  in  these  cases,  difference  of  fosm  implies  a  dif 
ference  of  interpretation  with  respect  to  the  auxiliary  symbol  r, 
and  each  form  is  interpretable  by  itself. 

Further,  these  differences  do  not  introduce  into  the  Calculus 
a  needless  perplexity.  It  will  hereafter  be  seen  that  they  give 
a  precision  and  a  definiteness  to  its  conclusions,  which  could  not 
otherwise  be  secured. 

Finally,  we  may  remark  that  all  the  equations  by  which 
particular  truths  are  expressed,  are  deducible  from  any  one 
general  equation,  expressing  any  one  general  Proposition,  from 
which  those  particular  Propositions  arc  necessary  deductions. 


24  OF    EXPRESSION    AND    INTERPRETATION. 

This  has  been  partially  shewn  already,  but  it  is  much  more  fully 
exemplified  in  the  following  scheme. 

The  general  equation  x  =  y, 

implies  that  the  classes  X  and  Y  are  equivalent,  member  for 
member ;  that  every  individual  belonging  to  the  one,  belongs 
to  the  other  also.  Multiply  the  equation  by  x,  and  we  have 

z*  =  xy ; 

/.  x  =  xy, 

which  implies,  by  (4),  that  all  Xs  are  Ys.  Multiply  the  same 
equation  by  y,  and  we  have  in  like  manner 

y  =  xy* 

the  import  of  which  is,  that  all  Ys  are  Xs.  Take  either  of  these 
equations,  the  latter  for  instance,  and  writing  it  under  the  form 

(i  -  *)  y  =  o, 

we  may  regard  it  as  an  equation  in  which  y,  an  unknown 
quantity,  is  sought  to  be  expressed  in  terms  of  x.  Now  it 
will  be  shewn  when  we  come  to  treat  of  the  Solution  of  Elective 
Equations  (and  the  result  may  here  be  verified  by  substitution) 
that  the  most  general  solution  of  this  equation  is 

y  =  *>*, 

which  implies  that  All  Ys  are  Xs,  and  that  Some  Xs  are  Ys. 
Multiply  by  xy  and  we  have 

vy  =  vx, 

which  indifferently  implies  that  some  Ys  are  Xs  and  some  Xs 
are  Ys,  being  the  particular  form  at  which  we  before  arrived. 

For  convenience  of  reference  the  above  and  some  other 
results  have  been  classified  in  the  annexed  Table,  the  first 
column  of  which  contains  propositions,  the  second  equations, 
and  the  third  the  conditions  of  final  interpretation.  It  is  to 
be  observed,  that  the  auxiliary  equations  which  are  given  in 
this  column  are  not  independent :  they  are  implied  either 
in  the  equations  of  the  second  column,  or  in  the  condition  for 


OF    EXPRESSION    AND    INTERPRETATION. 

the  interpretation  of  v.  But  it  has  been  thought  better  to  write 
them  separately,  for  greater  ease  and  convenience.  And  it  is 
further  to  be  borne  in  mind,  that  although  three  different  forms 
are  given  for  the  expression  of  each  of  the  particular  proposi 
tions,  everything  is  really  included  in  the  first  form. 

TABLE. 
The  class  X 
The  class  not-X 


All  Xs  are  Ys 
All  Ys  are  Xs 

All  Xs  are  Ys 
No  Xs  are  Ys 


i 
J 


i- 


/vx  -  some  Xs 
v  (1  -  x)  =  0. 

NoYsareXs         ^  ,  v  (1  -  *)  =  some  not-Xs 

Somenot-XsareYsr  ~  vx  =  0. 

C      v  =  xy  v  =  some  Xs  or  some  Ys 

Some  Xs  are  Ys     |  or  vx  =  vy  vx  =  some  Xs,  vy  =  some  Ys 

[or  vx  (1  -  y)  =  0  v  (1  -  x)  =  0,  v  (1  -  y)  =  0. 

C      v  =  x  (1  -  y)     v  =  some  Xs,  or  some  not-Ys 

Some  Xs  are  not  Ys  ]  or  vx  =  v  (1  -  y)    vx  =  some  Xs,  v  (1  -  y)  =  some  not-Ys 
I  or  vxy  =  0  v  (1  -  x)  =  0,  vy  =  0. 


OF  THE  CONVERSION  OF  PROPOSITIONS. 


A  Proposition  is  said  to  be  converted  when  its  terms  are  transposed ;  when 
nothing  more  is  done,  this  is  called  simple  conversion ;  e.g. 
No  virtuous  man  is  a  tyrant,  is  converted  into 
No  tyrant  is  a  virtuous  man. 

Logicians  also  recognise  conversion  per  accidens,  or  by  limitation,  e.g. 
All  birds  are  animals,  is  converted  into 
Some  animals  are  birds. 
And  conversion  by  contraposition  or  negation,  as 

Every  poet  is  a  man  of  genius,  converted  into 
He  who  is  not  a  man  of  genius  is  not  a  poet. 

In  one  of  these  three  ways  every  Proposition  may  be  illatively  converted,  viz. 
E  and  I  simply,  A  and  O  by  negation,  A  and  E  by  limitation. 

The  primary  canonical  forms  already  determined  for  the 
expression  of  Propositions,  are 

All  Xs  are  Ys,  x  (1  -  y)  =  0,  A. 

No  Xs  are  Ys,  xy  =  0,  .  .  . .  E. 

Some  Xs  are  Ys,  v  =  xy,  I. 

Some  Xs  are  not  Ys,  v  =  x  (1  -  y)  ...  .0. 

On  examining  these,  we  perceive  that  E  and  I  are  sym 
metrical  with  respect  to  x  and  y,  so  that  x  being  changed  into  y, 
and  y  into  x,  the  equations  remain  unchanged.  Hence  E  and  I 
may  be  interpreted  into 

No  Ys  are  Xs, 
Some  Ys  are  Xs, 

respectively.  Thus  we  have  the  known  rule  of  the  Logicians, 
that  particular  affirmative  and  universal  negative  Propositions 
admit  of  simple  conversion. 


OF    THE    CONVERSION    OF    PROPOSITIONS. 

The  equations  A  and  O  may  be  written  in  the  forms 


Now  these  are  precisely  the  forms  which  we  should  have 
obtained  if  we  had  in  those  equations  changed  x  into  1  -  y, 
and  y  into  1  -  x,  which  would  have  represented  the  changing 
in  the  original  Propositions  of  the  Xs  into  not-Ys,  and  the 
Ys  into  not-Xs,  the  resulting  Propositions  being 

All  not-Ys  are  not-Xs, 
Some  not-Ys  are  not  not-Xs  (a). 

Or  we  may,  by  simply  inverting  the  order  of  the  factors  in  the 
second  member  of  0,  and  writing  it  in  the  form 

v  =  (1  -  y)  xt 
interpret  it  by  I  into 

Some  not-Ys  are  Xs, 

which  is  really  another  form  of  (a).  Hence  follows  the  rule, 
that  universal  affirmative  and  particular  negative  Propositions 
admit  of  negative  conversion,  or,  as  it  is  also  termed,  conversion 
by  contraposition. 

The  equations  A  and  E,  written  in  the  forms 

(1  -  y)  x  =  0, 
yz=  0, 

give  on  solution  the  respective  forms 

x  =  vy, 
x  =  v  (1  -  y), 

the  correctness  of  which  may  be  shewn  by  substituting  these 
values  of  x  in  the  equations  to  which  they  belong,  and  observing 
that  those  equations  are  satisfied  quite  independently  of  the  nature 
of  the  symbol  v.  The  first  solution  may  be  interpreted  into 

Some  Ys  are  Xs, 
and  the  second  into 

Some  not-Ys  are  Xs. 


23  OF    THE    CONVERSION    OF    PROPOSITIONS. 

From  which  it  appears  that  universal-affirmative,  and  universal- 
negative  Propositions  are  convertible  by  limitation,  or,  as  it  has 
been  termed,  per  accidens. 

The  above  are  the  laws  of  Conversion  recognized  by  Abp. 
Whately.  Writers  differ  however  as  to  the  admissibility  of 
negative  conversion.  The  question  depends  on  whether  we  will 
consent  to  use  such  terms  as  not-X,  not-Y.  Agreeing  with 
those  who  think  that  such  terms  ought  to  be  admitted,  even 
although  they  change  the  kind  of  the  Proposition,  I  am  con 
strained  to  observe  that  the  present  classification  of  them  is 
faulty  and  defective.  Thus  the  conversion  of  No  Xs  are  Ys, 
into  All  Ys  are  not-Xs,  though  perfectly  legitimate,  is  not  re 
cognised  in  the  above  scheme.  It  may  therefore  be  proper  to 
examine  the  subject  somewhat  more  fully. 

Should  we  endeavour,  from  the  system  of  equations  we  have 
obtained,  to  deduce  the  laws  not  only  of  the  conversion,  but 
also  of  the  general  transformation  of  propositions,  we  should  be 
led  to  recognise  the  following  distinct  elements,  each  connected 
with  a  distinct  mathematical  process. 

1st.  The  negation  of  a  term,  i.  e.  the  changing  of  X  into  not-X, 
or  not-X  into  X. 

2nd.  The  translation  of  a  Proposition  from  one  kind  to 
another,  as  if  we  should  change 

All  Xs  are  Ys  into  Some  Xs  are  Ys        A  into  I, 
which  would  be  lawful ;    or 

All  Xs  are  Ys  into  No  Xs  are  Y.         A  into  E, 
which  would  be  unlawful. 

3rd.   The  simple  conversion  of  a  Proposition. 

The  conditions  in  obedience  to  which  these  processes  may 
lawfully  be  performed,  may  be  deduced  from  the  equations  by 
which  Propositions  are  expressed. 

We  have 

All  Xs  are  Ys x  (\  -  y)  =  0.         A, 

No  Xs  are  Ys xy  =  0.         E. 


OF    THE    CONVERSION    OF    PROPOSITIONS. 

Write  E  in  the  form 

*{i  -0  -y)}  =  o, 

and  it  is  interpretable  by  A  into 

All  Xs  are  not-Ys, 
so  that  we  may  change 

No  Xs  are  Ys  into  All  Xs  are  not-Ys. 
In  like  manner  A  interpreted  by  E  gives 

No  Xs  are  not-Ys, 
so  that  we  may  change 

All  Xs  are  Ys  into  No  Xs  are  not-Ys. 

From  these  cases  we  have  the  following  Rule :  A  universal- 
affirmative  Proposition  is  convertible  into  a  universal-negative, 
and,  vice  versd,  by  negation  of  the  predicate. 

Again,  we  have 

Some  Xs  are  Ys v  =  xy, 

Some  Xs  are  not  Ys  ....»  =  x  (1  -  y). 

These  equations  only  differ  from  those  last  considered  by  the 
presence  of  the  term  v.  The  same  reasoning  therefore  applies, 
and  we  have  the  Rule — 

A  particular-affirmative  proposition  is  convertible  into  a  par 
ticular-negative,  and  vice  versd,  by  negation  of  the  predicate. 
Assuming  the  universal  Propositions 

All  Xs  are  Ys- x  (\  -  y}  =  0, 

No  Xs  are  Ys xy  =  0. 

Multiplying  by  v,  we  find 

vx(\  -  y)  =  0, 

oxy  -  0, 
which  are  interpretable  into 

Some  Xs  are  Ys 1, 

Some  Xs  are  not  Ys.  .    .  O. 


30  OF    THE    CONVERSION    OF    PROPOSITIONS. 

Hence  a  universal-affirmative  is  convertible  into  a  particular- 
affirmative,  and  a  universal-negative  into  a  particular-negative 
without  negation  of  subject  or  predicate. 

Combining  the  above  with  the  already  proved  rule  of  simple 
conversion,  we  arrive  at  the  following  system  of  independent 
laws  of  transformation. 

1st.  An  affirmative  Proposition  may  be  changed  into  its  cor 
responding  negative  (A  into  E,  or  I  into  O),  and  vice  versa, 
by  negation  of  the  predicate. 

/ 

2nd.  A  universal  Proposition  may  be  changed  into  its  corre 
sponding  particular  Proposition,  (A  into  I,  or  E  into  O). 

3rd.  In  a  particular-affirmative,  or  universal-negative  Propo 
sition,  the  terms  may  be  mutually  converted. 

Wherein  negation  of  a  term  is  the  changing  of  X  into  not-X, 
and  vice  versd,  and  is  not  to  be  understood  as  affecting  the  kind 
of  the  Proposition. 

Every  lawful  transformation  is  reducible  to  the  above  rules. 
Thus  we  have 

All  Xs  are  Ys, 

No  Xs  are  not-Ys         by  1st  rule, 

No  not-Ys  are  Xs         by  3rd  rule, 

All  not-Ys  are  not-Xs  by  1st  rule, 
which  is  an  example  of  negative  conversion.     Again, 

No  Xs  are  Ys, 

No  Ys  are  Xs  3rd  rule, 

All  Ys  are  not-Xs        1st  rule, 
which  is  the  case  already  deduced. 


OF    SYLLOGISMS. 


A  Syllogism  consists  of  three  Propositions,  the  last  of  which,  called  the 
conclusion,  is  a  logical  consequence  of  the  two  former,  called  the  premises ; 

(All  Ys  are  Xs. 
Prennscs,     \^z&^^ 

Conclusion,     All  Zs  are  Xs. 

Every  syllogism  has  three  and  only  three  terms,  whereof  that  which  is 
the  subject  of  the  conclusion  is  called  the  minor  term,  the  predicate  of  the 
conclusion,  the  major  term,  and  the  remaining  term  common  to  both  premises, 
the  middle  term.  Thus,  in  ths  above  formula,  Z  is  the  minor  term,  X  the 
major  term,  Y  the  middle  term. 

The  figure  of  a  syllogism  consists  in  the  situation  of  the  middle  term  with 
respect  to  the  terms  of  the  conclusion.  The  varieties  of  figure  are  exhibited 
m  the  annexed  scheme. 

1st  Fig.  2nd  Fig.  3rd  Fig.  4th  Fig. 

YX  XY  YX  XY 
ZY  ZY  YZ  YZ 
ZX  ZX  ZX  ZX 

When  we  designate  the  three  propositions  of  a  syllogism  by  their  usual 
symbols  (A,  E,  I,  O),  and  in  their  actual  order,  we  are  said  to  determine 
the  mood  of  the  syllogism.  Thus  the  syllogism  given  above,  by  way  of 
illustration,  belongs  to  the  mood  AAA  in  the  first  figure. 

The  moods  of  all  syllogisms  commonly  received  as  valid,  are  represented 
by  the  vowels  in  the  following  mnemonic  verses. 

Fig.  1.— bArbArA,   cElArEnt,    dArll,   fErlO  que  pr'roris. 
Fig.  2.— cEsArE,  cAmEstrEs,  fEstlnQ  bArOkO,   secunda?. 
Fig.  3.— Tertia  dArAptl,  dlsAmls,  dAtlsI,  fElAptOn, 

bOkArdO,  fErlsO,  habet :  quarta  insuper  addit. 
Fig.  4.— brAmAntlp,  cAmEnEs,  dlmArls,  fEsapO,  frEsIsOn. 

TriE  equation  by  which  we  express  any  Proposition  con 
cerning  the  classes  X  and  Y,  is  an  equation  between  the 
symbols  x  and  y,  and  the  equation  by  which  we  express  any 


OF    SYLLOGISMS. 

Proposition  concerning  the  classes  Y  and  Z,  is  an  equation 
between  the  symbols  y  and  z.  If  from  two  such  equations 
we  eliminate  y,  the  result,  if  it  do  not  vanish,  will  be  an 
equation  between  x  and  *,  and  will  be  interpretable  into  a 
Proposition  concerning  the  classes  X  and  Z.  And  it  will  then 
constitute  the  third  member,  or  Conclusion,  of  a  Syllogism, 
of  which  the  two  given  Propositions  are  the  premises. 

The  result  of  the  elimination  of  y  from  the  equations 

«y+*-o, 

ay  +  £  =  0, 


is  the  equation  ab'  -  a'b  =  0, 

Now  the  equations  of  Propositions  being  of  the  first  order 
with  reference  to  each  of  the  variables  involved,  all  the  cases 
of  elimination  which  we  shall  have  to  consider,  will  be  re 
ducible  to  the  above  case,  the  constants  a,  b,  d  ,  b',  being' 
replaced  by  functions  of  x,  z,  and  the  auxiliary  symbol  v. 

As  to  the  choice  of  equations  for  the  expression  of  our 
premises,  the  only  restriction  is,  that  the  equations  must  not 
both  be  of  the  form  ay  =  0,  for  in  such  cases  elimination  would 
be  impossible.  When  both  equations  are  of  this  form,  it  is 
necessary  to  solve  one  of  them,  and  it  is  indifferent  which 
we  choose  for  this  purpose.  If  that  which  we  select  is  of 
the  form  xy  =  0,  its  solution  is 

y  «»(!-*),     (16), 

if  of  the  form  (1  -  x)  y  =  0,  the  solution  will  be 

y  =  vx,     (17), 

and  these  are  the  only   cases   which  can  arise.     The  reason 
of  this  exception  will  appear  in  the  sequel. 

For  the  sake  of  uniformity  we  shall,  in  the  expression  of 
particular  propositions,  confine  ourselves  to  the  forms 

DX  =  0y,  Some  Xs  are  Ys, 

vx  =  v  (1  -  y\        Some  Xs  are  not  Ys, 


OF    SYLLOGISMS.  S3 

These  have  a  closer  analogy  with  (16)  and  (17),  than  the  other 
forms  which  might  be  used. 

Between  the  forms  about  to  be  developed,  and  the  Aristotelian 
canons,  some  points  of  difference  will  occasionally  be  observed, 
of  which  it  may  be  proper  to  forewarn  the  reader. 

To  the  right  understanding  of  these  it  is  proper  to  remark, 
that  the  essential  structure  of  a  Syllogism  is,  in  some  measure, 
arbitrary.  Supposing  the  order  of  the  premises  to  be  fixed, 
and  the  distinction  of  the  major  and  the  minor  term  to  be 
thereby  determined,  it  is  purely  a  matter  of  choice  which  of 
the  two  shall  have  precedence  in  the  Conclusion.  Logicians 
have  settled  this  question  in  favour  of  the  minor  term,  but 
it  is  clear,  that  this  is  a  convention.  Had  it  been  agreed 
that  the  major  term  should  have  the  first  place  in  the  con 
clusion,  a  logical  scheme  might  have  been  constructed,  less 
convenient  in  some  cases  than  the  existing  one,  but  superior 
in  others.  What  it  lost  in  barbara,  it  would  gain  in  Iramantip. 
Convenience  is  perhaps  in  favour  of  the  adopted  arrangement,* 
but  it  is  to  be  remembered  that  it  is  merely  an  arrangement. 

Now  the  method  we  shall  exhibit,  not  having  reference 
to  one  scheme  of  arrangement  more  than  to  another,  will 
always  give  the  more  general  conclusion,  regard  being  paid 
only  to  its  abstract  lawfulness,  considered  as  a  result  of  pure 
reasoning.  And  therefore  we  shall  sometimes  have  presented 
to  us  the  spectacle  of  conclusions,  which  a  logician  would 
pronounce  informal,  but  never  of  such  as  a  reasoning  being 
would  account  false. 

The  Aristotelian  canons,  however,  beside  restricting  the  order 
of  the  terms  of  a  conclusion,  limit  their  nature  also; — and 
this  limitation  is  of  more  consequence  than  the  former.  We 
may,  by  a  change  of  figure,  replace  the  particular  conclusion 

*  The  contrary  view  was  maintained  by  Hobbes.  The  question  is  very 
fairly  discussed  in  Hallam's  Introduction  to  the  Literature  of  Europe,  vol.  in. 
p.  309.  In  the  rhetorical  use  of  Syllogism,  the  advantage  appears  to  rest 
with  the  rejected  form. 


04  ON    SYLLOGISMS. 

of  Iramantipy  by  the  general   conclusion  of  barbara;  but  we 
cannot  thus  reduce  to  rule  such  inferences,  as 

Some  not-Xs  are  not  Ys. 

Yet  there  are  cases  in  which  such  inferences  may  lawfully 
be  drawn,  and  in  unrestricted  argument  they  are  of  frequent 
occurrence.  Now  if  an  inference  of  this,  or  of  any  other 
kind,  is  lawful  in  itself,  it  will  be  exhibited  in  the  results 
of  our  method. 

We  may  by  restricting  the  canon  of  interpretation  confine 
our  expressed  results  within  the  limits  of  the  scholastic  logic; 
but  this  would  only  be  to  restrict  ourselves  to  the  use  of  a  part 
of  the  conclusions  to  which  our  analysis  entitles  us. 

The  classification  we  shall  adopt  will  be  purely  mathematical, 
and  we  shall  afterwards  consider  the  logical  arrangement  to 
which  it  corresponds.  It  will  be  sufficient,  for  reference,  to 
name  the  premises  and  the  Figure  in  which  they  are  found. 

CLASS  1st. — Forms  in  which  v  does  not  enter. 

Those  which  admit  of  an  inference  are  AA,  EA,  Fig.  1  ; 
AE;  EA,  Fig.  2;  A  A,  AE,  Fig.  4. 

Ex.  A  A,  Fig.  1,  and,  by  mutation  of  premises  (change  of 
order),  A  A,  Fig.  4. 

All  Ys  are  Xs,          y  (1  -  x)  =  0,          or  (1  -  x)  y  =  0, 
All  Zs  are  Ys,  z  (1  -  y)=  0,  or       zy  -  z  =  Q. 

Eliminating  y  by  (lo)  we  have 

z  (1  -  x)  =  0, 
.-.  All  Zs  are  Xs. 

A  convenient  mode  of  effecting  the  elimination,  is  to  write 
the  equation  of  the  premises,  so  that  y  shall  appear  only  as 
a  factor  of  one  member  in  the  first  equation,  and  only  as 
a  factor  of  the  opposite  member  in  the  second  equation,  and 
then  to  multiply  the  equations,  omitting  the  y.  This  method 
we  shall  adopt. 


OF    SYLLOGISMS.  35 

Ex.    AE,  Fig.  2,  and,  by  mutation  of  premises,  E  A,  Fig,  2. 
All  Xs  are  Ys,          x  (1  -  y)  =  0,          or     x  «=  xy 
No  Zs  are  Ys,  zy     =  0,  zy  =  0 

;*r=0 

.*.  No  Zs  are  Xs. 

The  only  case  in  which  there  is  no  inference  is  A  A,  Fig.  2, 
AllXsareYs,  *(l-«/)=0,  x  =  xy 

All  Zs  are  Ys,  z  (1  -  y)  =  o,  zy  =  z 

£2  =  #Z 

.'.    0=0. 

CLASS  2nd. — When  v  is  introduced  by  the  solution  of  an 
equation. 

The  lawful  cases  directly  or  indirectly*  determinable  by  the 
Aristotelian  Rules  are  AE,  Fig.  1;  A  A,  AE,  EA,  Fig.  3; 
EA,  Fig.  4. 

The  lawful  cases  not  so  determinable,  are  EE,  Fig.  1 ;  EE, 
Fig  2;  EE,  Fig.  3;  EE,  Fig.  4. 

Ex.    AE,  Fig.  1,  and,  by  mutation  of  premises,  EA,  Fig.  4. 
All  Ys  are  Xs,  y  (1  -  x)  =  0,  y  =  vx     (a) 

No  Zs  are  Ys,  zy     =0,  0  =  zy 

0  =  vzz 

:.  Some  Xs  are  not  Zs. 

The  reason  why  we  cannot  interpret  vzz  =  0  into  Some  Zs 
are  not-Xs,  is  that  by  the  very  terms  of  the  first  equation  (a) 
the  interpretation  of  vx  is  fixed,  as  Some  Xs  ;  v  is  regarded 
as  the  representative  of  Some,  only  with  reference  to  the 
class  X. 

*  We  say  directly  or  indirectly,  mutation  or  conversion  of  premises  being 
in  some  instances  required.  Thus,  AE  (fig.  1)  is  resolvable  by  Fesapo  (fig.  4), 
or  by  Ferio  (fig.  1).  Aristotle  and  his  followers  rejected  the  fourth  figure 
as  only  a  modification  of  the  first,  but  this  being  a  mere  question  of  form, 
either  scheme  may  be  termed  Aristotelian. 


36  OF    SYLLOGISMS. 

For  the  reason  of  our  employing  a  solution  of  one  of  the 
primitive  equations,  see  the  remarks  on  (16)  and  (17).  Had 
we  solved  the  second  equation  instead  of  the  first,  we  should 
have  had 

(l-a?)y=0, 
tj(l-*0  =  y,    (a), 
v(\-z)  (l-*)  =  0,     (£), 
.*.  Some  not-Zs  are  Xs. 

Here  it  is  to  be  observed,  that  the  second  equation  (a)  fixes 
the  meaning  of  v(\  -2),  as  Some  not-Zs.  The  full  meaning 
of  the  result  (b)  is,  that  all  the  not-Zs  which  are  found  in 
the  class  Y  are  found  in  the  class  X,  and  it  is  evident  that 
this  could  not  have  been  expressed  in  any  other  way. 

Ex.  2.    AA,  Fig.  3. 

All  Ys  are  Xs,         y  (1  -  a?)  =  0,         y  =  vx 

All  Ys  are  Zs,          y  (1  -  2)  =  0,         Q  =  y(l-z) 

0  =  vx(\  -  z) 
:.  Some  Xs  are  Zs. 

Had  we  solved  the  second  equation,  we  should  have  had 
as  our  result,  Some  Zs  are  Xs.  The  form  of  the  final  equation 
particularizes  what  Xs  or  what  Zs  are  referred  to,  and  this 
remark  is  general. 

The  following,  EE,  Fig.  1,  and,  by  mutation,  EE,  Fig.  4, 
is  an  example  of  a  lawful  case  not  determinable  by  the  Aris 
totelian  Rules. 

No  Ys  are  Xs,          xy  =  0,          0  =  xy 

No  Zs  are  Ys,  zy  =  0,          y  =  v  (1  -  2) 

0  =  v  (1  -  2)  x 
:.  Some  not-Zs  are  not  Xs. 

CLASS  3rd. — When  v  is  met  with  in  one  of  the  equations, 
but  not  introduced  by  solution. 


OF    SYLLOGISMS.  37 

The  lawful  cases  determinable  directly  or  indirectly  by  the 
Aristotelian  Rules,  are  AI,  El,  Fig.  1 ;  AO,  El,  OA,  IE, 
Fig.  2;  AI,  AO,  El,  EO,  IA,  IE,  OA,  OE,  Fig.  3;  IA,  IE, 
Fig.  4. 

Those  not  so  determinable  are  OE,  Fig.  1  ;  EO,  Fig.  4. 

The  cases  in  which  no  inference  is  possible,  are  AO,  EO, 
I  A,  IE,  OA,  Fig.  1;  AI,  EO,  IA,  OE,  Fig.  2;  OA,  OE, 
AI,  El,  AO,  Fig.  4. 

Ex.  1.    AI,  Fig.  1,  and,  by  mutation,  I  A,  Fig.  4. 
All  Ys  are  Xs,  y  (1  -  x)  =   0 

Some  Zs  are  Ys,  vz     =  vy 

vz(l  -  *)=   0 
/.  Some  Zs  are  Xs, 

Ex.  2.    AO,  Fig.  2,  and,  by  mutation,  OA,  Fig.  2. 
All  Xs  are  Ys,  #(l-y)=o,  x  =  xy 

Some  Zs  are  not  Ys,  vz  =  v(l-y\         vy  =  v(\-z) 

tx  =  vx(\-z) 
vzz  =  0 
:.  Some  Zs  are  not  Xs. 

The  interpretation  of  vz  as  Some  Zs,  is  implied,  it  will  be 
observed,  in  the  equation  vz  =  v  ( 1  -  y)  considered  as  repre 
senting  the  proposition  Some  Zs  are  not  Ys. 

The  cases  not  determinable  by  the  Aristotelian  Rules  are 
OE,  Fig.  1,  and,  by  mutation,  EO,  Fig.  4. 

Some  Ys  are  not  Xs,  vy  =  v  (1  -  x) 

No  Zs  are  Ys,  o  =  Zy 

0  =  v  (1  -  x)  z 
/.  Some  not-Xs  are  not  Zs. 

The  equation  of  the  first- premiss  here  permits  us  to  interpret 
c  (l  -  #)>  but  it  does  not  enable  us  to  interpret  vz. 

D2 


38  OF    SYLLOGISMS. 

Of  cases  in  which  no  inference  is  possible,  we  take  as 
examples — 

AO,  Fig.  1,  and,  by  mutation,  OA,  Fig.  4, 
AllYsareXs,  2/(l-z)=0,  y(\-x)=Q 

Some  Zs  are  not  Ys,  vz  -  v  (1  -  y)    (a)       v(l  -z)  =  vy 

i>(l-*)(l-aO-0   ») 
0  =  0 

since  the  auxiliary  equation  in  this  case  is  v  (1  -  z)  =  0. 

Practically  it  is  not  necessary  to  perform  this  reduction,  but 
it  is  satisfactory  to  do  so.  The  equation  (a),  it  is  seen,  defines 
vz  as  Some  Zs,  but  it  does  not  define  v  (1  -  z),  so  that  we  might 
stop  at  the  result  of  elimination  (If),  and  content  ourselves  with 
saying,  that  it  is  not  interpretable  into  a  relation  between  the 
classes  X  and  Z. 

Take  as  a  second  example  AT,  Fig.  2,  and,  by  mutation, 
IA,  Fig.  2, 

AllXsareYs,  s(l-y)=0,  x  =  xy 

Some  Zs  are  Ys,  vz  =  vy,          vy  =  vz 

vz  =  vxz 
0(1  -z)x=Q 
0  =  0, 
the  auxiliary  equation  in  this  case  being  0(1  -  *)=  0. 

Indeed  in  every  case  in  this  class,  in  which  no  inference 
is  possible,  the  result  of  elimination  is  reducible  to  the  form 
0  =  0.  Examples  therefore  need  not  be  multiplied. 

CLASS  4th. — When  v  enters  into  both  equations, 
No  inference  is  possible  in  any  case,  but  there  exists  a  dis 
tinction  among   the  unlawful  cases  which  is  peculiar  to  this 
class.     The  two  divisions  are, 

1st.  When  the  result  of  elimination  is  reducible  by  the 
auxiliary  equations  to  the  form  0  =  0.  The  cases  are  II,  OI, 


OF    SYLLOGISMS.  39 

Fig.  1;    II,   00,    Fig.  2  ;    II,   10,   01,   00,    Fig.  3;    II,    10, 
Fig.  4. 

2nd.   When  the  result  of  elimination  is  not  reducible  by  the 
auxiliary  equations  to  the  form  0  =  0. 

The  cases  are  1O,  OO,   Fig.  1;    10,  OI,  Fig.  2;   OI,  00, 
Fig.  4. 

Let  us  take  as  an  example  of  the  former  case,  II,  Fig.  3. 
Some  Xs  are  Ys,  vx  =  vy,  vx  =  vy 

Some  Zs  are  Ys,  v'z  =  v'y,  v'y  =  v'z 

vv'x  —  vv'z 

Now  the  auxiliary  equations  v  (1  -  x)  =  0,  v  (1  -  z)  =  0, 
give   vx  =  v,     v'z  =  v'. 

Substituting  we  have 

vv'  =  vv', 

.-.  0  =  0. 
As  an  example  of  the  latter  case,  let  us  take  10,  Fig.  1 , 

Some  Ys  are  Xs,  vy  =  vx,  vy  =  vx 

Some  Zs  are  not  Ys,         v'z  =  v'  (1  -  y),          v  (1  -  z)  =  v'y 


vv'  (I  -z}-  vv'x 

Now  the  auxiliary  equations  being  v  (1  -  x)  =  0,  v'  (1  -  z)  =  0, 
the  above  reduces  to  vv  =  0.  It  is  to  this  form  that  all  similar 
cases  are  reducible.  Its  interpretation  is,  that  the  classes  v 
and  v  have  nc  common  member,  as  is  indeed  evident. 

The  above  classification  is  purely  founded  on  mathematical 
distinctions.  We  shall  now  inquire  what  is  the*  logical  division 
to  which  it  corresponds. 

The  lawful  cases  of  the  first  class  comprehend  all  those  in 
which,  from  two  universal  premises,  a  universal  conclusion 
may  be  drawn.  We  see  that  they  include  the  premises  of 
barbara  and  celarent  in  the  first  figure,  of  cesare  and  camcstrcs 
in  the  second,  and  of  bramantip  and  camcnes  in  the  fourth. 


40  OF   SYLLOGISMS, 

The  premises  of  bramantip  are  included,   because  they  admit 
of  an  universal  conclusion,  although  not  in  the  same  figure. 

The  lawful  cases  of  the  second  class  are  those  in  which 
a  particular  conclusion  only  is  deducible  from  two  universal 
premises. 

The  lawful  cases  of  the  third  class  are  those  in  which  a 
conclusion  is  deducible  from  two  premises,  one  of  which  is 
universal  and  the  other  particular. 

The  fourth  class  has  no  lawful  cases. 

Among  the  cases  in  which  no  inference  of  any  kind  is  pos 
sible,  we  find  six  in  the  fourth  class  distinguishable  from  the 
others  by  the  circumstance,  that  the  result  of  elimination  does 
not  assume  the  form  0  =  0.  The  cases  are 

f  Some  Ys  are  Xs,    "\  f  Some  Ys  are  not  Xs,]  f  Some  Xs  are  Ys,    "I 
\Some  Zs  are  not  Ys,J  \Some  Zs  are  not  Ys, j  (Some  Zs  are  not  Ys,/ 

and    the   three    others    which   are    obtained    by   mutation   of 
premises. 

It  might  be  presumed  that  some  logical  peculiarity  would 
be  found  to  answer  to  the  mathematical  peculiarity  which  we 
have  noticed,  and  in  fact  there  exists  a  very  remarkable  one. 
If  we  examine  each  pair  of  premises  in  the  above  scheme,  we 
shall  find  that  there  is  virtually  no  middle  term,  i.  e.  no  medium 
of  comparison,  in  any  of  them.  Thus,  in  the  first  example, 
the  individuals  spoken  of  in  the  first  premiss  are  asserted  to 
belong  to  the  class  Y,  but  those  spoken  of  in  the  second 
premiss  are  virtually  asserted  to  belong  to  the  class  not-Y: 
nor  can  we  by  any  lawful  transformation  or  conversion  alter 
this  state  of  things.  The  comparison  will  still  be  made  with 
the  class  Y  in  one  premiss,  and  with  the  class  not-Y  in  the 
other. 

Now  in  every  case  beside  the  above  six,  there  will  be  found 
a  middle  term,  either  expressed  or  implied.  I  select  two 
of  the  most  difficult  cases. 


OF     SYLLOGISMS.  41 

In  AO,  Fig.  1,  viz. 

All  Ys  are  Xs, 
Some  Zs  are  not  Ys, 

we  have,  by  negative  conversion  of  the  first  premiss, 

All  not-Xs  are  not-Ys, 
Some  Zs  are  not  Ys, 

and  the  middle  term  is  now  seen  to  be  not-Y. 
Again,  in  EO,  Fig.  1, 

.  •  No  Ys  are  Xs, 

Some  Zs  are  not  Ys, 

a  proved  conversion  of  the  first  premiss  (see  Conversion  of 
Propositions),  gives 

All  Xs  are  not-Ys, 

Some  Zs  are  not-Ys, 

and  the  middle  term,  the  true  medium  of  comparison,  is  plainly 
not-Y,  although  as  the  not-Ys  in  the  one  premiss  may  be 
different  from  those  in  the  other,  no  conclusion  can  be  drawn. 

The  mathematical  condition  in  question,  therefore, — the  irre- 
ducibility  of  the  final  equation  to  the  form  0  =  0, — adequately 
represents  the  logical  condition  of  there  being  no  middle  term, 
or  common  medium  of  comparison,  in  the  given  premises. 

I  am  not  aware  that  the  distinction  occasioned  by  the 
presence  or  absence  of  a  middle  term,  in  the  strict  sense  here 
understood,  has  been  noticed  by  logicians  before.  The  dis 
tinction,  though  real  and  deserving  attention,  is  indeed  by 
no  means  an  obvious  one,  and  it  would  have  been  unnoticed 
in  the  present  instance  but  for  the  peculiarity  of  its  mathe 
matical  expression. 

What  appears  to  be  novel  in  the  above  case  is  the  proof 
of  the  existence  of  combinations  of  premises  in  which  there 


OF    SYLLOGISMS. 

is  absolutely  no  medium  of  comparison.  When  such  a  medium 
of  comparison,  or  true  middle  term,  does  exist,  the  condition 
that  its  quantification  in  both  premises  together  shall  ex 
ceed  its  quantification  as  a  single  whole,  has  been  ably  and 
clearly  shewn  by  Professor  De  Morgan  to  be  necessary  to 
lawful  inference  (Cambridge  Memoirs,  Vol.  vm.  Part  3).  And 
this  is  undoubtedly  the  true  principle  of  the  Syllogism,  viewed 
from  the  standing-point  of  Arithmetic. 

I  have  said  that  it  would  be  possible  to  impose  conditions 
of  interpretation  which  should  restrict  the  results  of  this  cal 
culus  to  the  Aristotelian  forms.  Those  conditions  would  be, 

1st.  That  we  should  agree  not  to  interpret  the  forms  v(l  -  x), 
v(l-z). 

2ndly.  That  we  should  agree  to  reject  every  interpretation  in 
which  the  order  of  the  terms  should  violate  the  Aristotelian  rule. 

Or,  instead  of  the  second  condition,  it  might  be  agreed  that, 
the  conclusion  being  determined,  the  order  of  the  premises 
should,  if  necessary,  be  changed,  so  as  to  make  the  syllogism 
formal. 

From  the  general  character  of  the  system  it  is  indeed  plain, 
that  it  may  be  made  to  represent  any  conceivable  scheme  of 
logic,  by  imposing  the  conditions  proper  to  the  case  con 
templated. 

We  have  found  it,  in  a  certain  class  of  cases,  to  be  necessary 
to  replace  the  two  equations  expressive  of  universal  Propo 
sitions,  by  their  solutions;  and  it  may  be  proper  to  remark, 
that  it  would  have  been  allowable  in  all  instances  to  have 
done  this,*  so  that  every  case  of  the  Syllogism,  without  ex- 

*  It  may  be  satisfactory  to  illustrate  this  statement  by  an  example.  In 
Barbara,  we  should  have 

All  Ys  are  Xs,  y  =  vx 

All  Zs  are  Ys,  z  =  v'y 

z  =  vv'x 
.'.  All  Zs  are  Xs. 


OF    SYLLOGISMS. 


43 


ception,  might  have  been  treated  by  equations  comprised  in 
the  general  forms 

y  =  vx,  or         y  -  vx  =  0  .  .  .  .  A, 

y  =  v  (1  -  x),  or  y  +  vx  -  v  =  0  .  . . .  E, 

vy  =  vx,  vy  -  vx  =  0  .  . . .  I, 

vy  =  v  (i  _  x),  vy  +  vx  -  v  =  0  .  .  . .  O. 

Or,  we  may  multiply  the  resulting  equation  by  1  -  x,  which  gives 

.(l-.)-O, 

whence  the  same  conclusion,  All  Zs  are  Xs. 

Some  additional  examples  of  the  application  of  the  system  of  equations  in 
the  text  to  the  demonstration  of  general  theorems,  may  not  be  inappropriate. 

Let  y  be  the  term  to  be  eliminated,  and  let  x  stand  indifferently  for  either  of 
the  other  symbols,  then  each  of  the  equations  of  the  premises  of  any  given 
syllogism  may  be  put  in  the  form 

ay  +  bx  =  0,     (a) 
if  the  premiss  is  affirmative,  and  in  the  form 

ay +  6(1-*)  =  0,     (/3) 

if  it  is  negative,  a  and  b  being  either  constant,  or  of  the  form  ±  v.  To  prove 
this  in  detail,  let  us  examine  each  kind  of  proposition,  making  y  successively 
subject  and  predicate. 

A,   All  Ys  are  Xs,  y  -  vx  =  0,  (y), 

All  Xs  are  Ys,  x  -  vy  =  0,  (*), 

E,   No  Ys  are  Xs,  xy  =  0, 

No  Xs  are  Ys,  y  -  v  (1  -  a?)  =  0,  («), 

I,    Some  Xs  are  Ys, 

Some  Ys  are  Xs,  vx  -  vy  =  0,  (£)» 

O,   Some  Ys  are  not  Xs,        vy  —  v  (1  -  x)  =  0,  (»»), 

Some  Xs  are  not  Ys,  vx  =  v  (1  —  y), 

...  vy  _  „  (i  _  3.)  =0,  (0). 

The  affirmative  equations  (y),  (<$)  and  (£),  belong  to.  (a),  and  the  negative 
equations  («),  (tj)  and  (0),  to  (/3).  It  is  seen  that  the  two  last  negative  equa 
tions  are  alike,  but  there  is  a  difference  of  interpretation.  In  the  former 

v  (1  —  ar)  =  Some  not-Xs, 
in  the  latter,  v  (1  -  a?)  =  0. 

The  utility  of  the  two  general  forms  of  reference,  («)  and  (/3),  will  appear 
from  the  following  application. 

1st.    A  conclusion  drawn  from  two  affirmative  propositions  is  itself  affirmative. 
By  (a)  we  have  for  the  given  propositions, 
ay  +  bx  =  0, 
ay  -\-  b'z  —  0, 


44  OF    SYLLOGISMS. 

Perhaps  the  system   we   have  actually  employed   is   better, 
as  distinguishing  the  cases  in  which  v  only  may  be  employed, 

and  eliminating  ab>z  _  a'bx  =  0, 

which  is  of  the  form  (a) .     Hence,  if  there  is  a  conclusion,  it  is  affirmative. 

2nd.  A  conclusion  drawn  from  an  affirmative  and  a  negative  proposition  is 
negative. 

By  (a)  and  (/3),  we  have  for  the  given  propositions 

ay  +  bx  —  0, 
ay  +  b'  (1  -  *)  =  0, 

.'.  a'bx  -  ab'  (1  —  z)  =  0, 

which  is  of  the  form  (/3) .     Hence  the  conclusion,  if  there  is  one,  is  negative. 

3rd.    A  conclusion  draicn  from  two  negative  premises  will  involve  a  negation, 
(no£-X,  not-Z)  in  both  subject  and  predicate,  and  will  therefore  be  inadmissible  in 
the  Aristotelian  system,  though  just  in  itself. 
For  the  premises  being 

ay  +  b  (1  -  a?)  =  0, 
ay  +  b'  (1  -  z)  =  0, 
the  conclusion  will  be 

ab'  (1  -  2)  -  a'b  (1  -  ar)  =  0, 

which  is  only  interpretable  into  a  proposition  that  has  a  negation  in  each  term. 

4th.  Taking  into  account  those  syllogisms  only,  in  ichich  the  conclusion  is  the 
most  general,  that  can  be  deduced  from  the  premises, — if,  in  an  Aristotelian 
syllogism,  the  minor  premises  be  changed  in  quality  (from  affirmative  to  negative 
or  from  negative  to  affirmative),  whether  it  be  changed  in  quantity  or  not,  no  con 
clusion  will  be  deducible  in  the  same  figure. 

An  Aristotelian  proposition  does  not  admit  a  term  of  the  form  not-Z  in  the 
subject, — Now  on  changing  the  quantity  of  the  minor  proposition  of  a  syllogism, 
we  transfer  it  from  the  general  form 

ay  +  bz  =  0, 
to  the  general  form  a'y  +  &'  (1  -  *)  =  0, 

see  (a)  and  (/3),  or  vice  versd.  And  therefore,  in  the  equation  of  the  conclusion, 
there  will  be  a  change  from  z  to  1  —  *,,  or  vice  versd.  But  this  is  equivalent  to 
the  change  of  Z  into  not-Z,  or  not-Z  into  Z.  Now  the  subject  of  the  original 
conclusion  must  have  involved  a  Z  and  not  a  not-Z,  therefore  the  subject  of  the 
new  conclusion  will  involve  a  not-Z,  and  the  conclusion  will  not  be  admissible 
in  the  Aristotelian  forms,  except  by  conversion,  which  would  render  necessary 
a  change  of  Figure. 

Now  the  conclusions  of  this  calculus  are  always  the  most  general  that  can  be 
drawn,  and  therefore  the  above  demonstration  must  not  be  supposed  to  extend 
to  a  syllogism,  in  which  a  particular  conclusion  is  deduced,  when  a  universal 
one  is  possible.  This  is  the  case  with  bramantip  only,  among  the  Aristotelian 
forms,  and  therefore  the  transformation  of  bramantip  into  camenes,  and  vice  versd, 
is  the  case  of  restriction  contemplated  in  the  preliminary  statement  of  the 
theorem. 


OF    SYLLOGISMS. 


45 


from  those  in  which  it  must.  But  for  the  demonstration  of 
certain  general  properties  of  the  Syllogism,  the  above  system 
is,  from  its  simplicity,  and  from  the  mutual  analogy  of  its 
forms,  very  convenient.  We  shall  apply  it  to  the  following 
theorem.* 

Given  the  three  propositions  of  a  Syllogism,  prove  that  there 
is  but  one  order  in  which  they  can  be  legitimately  arranged, 
and  determine  that  order. 

All  the  forms  above  given  for  the  expression  of  propositions, 
are  particular  cases  of  the  general  form, 
a  +  bx  +  cy  =  0. 

5th.  If  for  the  minor  premiss  of  an  Aristotelian  syllogism,  we  substitute  its  con 
tradictory,  no  conclusion  is  deducible  in  the  same  figure. 

It  is  here  only  necessary  to  examine  the  case  of  bramantip,  all  the  others 
being  determined  by  the  last  proposition. 

On  changing  the  minor  of  bramantip  to  its  contradictory,  we  have  AO, 
Fig.  4,  and  this  admits  of  no  legitimate  inference. 

Hence  the  theorem  is  true  without  exception.  Many  other  general  theorems 
may  in  like  manner  be  proved. 

*  This  elegant  theorem  was  communicated  by  the  Rev.  Charles  Graves, 
Fellow  and  Professor  of  Mathematics  in  Trinity  College,  Dublin,  to  whom  the 
Author  desires  further  to  record  his  grateful  acknowledgments  for  a  very 
judicious  examination  of  the  former  portion  of  this  work,  and  for  some  new 
applications  of  the  method.  The  following  example  of  Reduction  ad  impossible 
is  among  the  number  : 

Reducend  Mood,   All  Xs  are  Ys,  1  -  y  =  t>'  (1  -  .r) 

Baroko  Some  Zs  axe  not  Ys  w  =  v  (1  -  y) 

Some  Zs  are  not  Xs  vz  =  vv'  (1  -  x) 

Reduct  Mood,  All  Xs  are  Ys  1  -  y  =  V  (1  -  *) 

Barbara         All  Zs  are  Xs *  (\  -  x)  =  0  * 

All  Zs  are  Ys  *  (1  -  y)  =  0. 

The  conclusion  of  the  reduct  mood  is  seen  to  be  the  contradictory  of  the 
suppressed  minor  premiss.  Whence,  &c.  It  may  just  be  remarked  that  the 
mathematical  test  of  contradictory  propositions  is,  that  on  eliminating  one 
elective  symbol  between  their  equations,  the  other  elective  symbol  vanishes. 
The  ostensive  reduction  of  Baroko  and  Bokardo  involves  no  difficulty. 

Professor  Graves  suggests  the  employment  of  the  equation  a:  =  vy  for  the 
primary  expression  of  the  Proposition  All  Xs  are  Ys,  and  remarks,  that  on 
multiplying  both  members  by  1  -  y,  we  obtain  .r  (1  -  y)  =  0,  the  equation  from 
which  we  set  out  in  the  text,  and  of  which  the  previous  one  is  a  solution. 


46  OF    SYLLOGISMS. 

Assume  then  for  the  premises  of  the  given  syllogism,  the 

equations 

a  +  bx  +  cy  =  0,     (18), 

a  +  b'z  +  c'y  =  0,     (19), 

then,  eliminating  y>  we  shall  have  for  the  conclusion 
ad  -  a'c  +  bc'x  -  b'cz  =  0,     (20). 

Now  taking  this  as  one  of  our  premises,  and  either  of  the 
original  equations,  suppose  (18),  as  the  other,  if  by  elimination 
of  a  common  term  x,  between  them,  we  can  obtain  a  result 
equivalent  to  the  remaining  premiss  (19),  it  will  appear  that 
there  are  more  than  one  order  in  which  the  Propositions  may 
be  lawfully  written ;  but  if  otherwise,  one  arrangement  only 
is  lawful. 

Effecting  then  the  elimination,  we  have 

be  (a1  +  b'z  +  c'y}=  0,     (21), 

which  is  equivalent  to  (19)  multiplied  by  a  factor  be.  Now  on 
examining  the  value  of  this  factor  in  the  equations  A,  E,  I,  O, 
we  find  it  in  each  case  to  be  v  or  -  v.  But  it  is  evident, 
that  if  an  equation  expressing  a  given  Proposition  be  mul 
tiplied  by  an  extraneous  factor,  derived  from  another  equa 
tion,  its  interpretation  will  either  be  limited  or  rendered 
impossible.  Thus  there  will  either  be  no  result  at  all,  or  the 
result  will  be  a  limitation  of  the  remaining  Proposition. 

If,  however,  one  of  the  original  equations  were 
x  =  y,         or    x  -  y  =  0, 

the  factor  be  would  be  -  1,  and  would  not  limit  the  interpret 
ation  of  the  other  premiss.  Hence  if  the  first  member  of 
a  syllogism  should  be  understood  to  represent  the  double 
proposition  All  Xs  are  Ys,  and  All  Ys  are  Xs,  it  would  be 
indifferent  in  what  order  the  remaining  Propositions  were 
written. 


OF     SYLLOGISMS.  47 

A  more  general  form  of  the  above  investigation  would  be, 
to  express  the  premises  by  the  equations 

a  +  bx  +  cy  +  dxy  =  0,     (22), 
a'+b'z  +  cy  +  d'zy  =  0,     (23). 

After  the  double  elimination  of  y  and  x  we  should  find 
(be  -  ad}  (a  +  b'z  +  cy  +  d'zy)  =  0 ; 

and  it  would  be  seen  that  the  factor  be  -  ad  must  in  every 
case  either  vanish  or  express  a  limitation  of  meaning. 

The  determination  of  the  order  of  the  Propositions  is  suf 
ficiently  obvious. 


OF  HYPOTHETICALS. 


A  hypothetical  Proposition  is  defined  to  be  two  or  more  categorical*  united  by 
a  copula  (or  conjunction),  and  the  different  kinds  of  hypothetical  Propositions 
are  named  from  their  respective  conjunctions,  viz.  conditional  (if)  disjunctive 
(either,  or),  &c. 

In  conditionals,  that  categorical  Proposition  from  which  the  other  results 
is  called  the  antecedent,  that  which  results  from  it  the  consequent. 

Of  the  conditional  syllogism  there  are  two,  and  only  two  formula?. 

1st.   The  constructive, 

If  A  is  B,  then  C  is  D, 
But  A  is  B,  therefore  C  is  D. 

2nd.  The  Destructive, 

If  A  is  B,  then  C  is  D, 
But  C  is  not  D,  therefore  A  is  not  B. 

A  dilemma  is  a  complex  conditional  syllogism,  with  several  antecedents 
in  the  major,  and  a  disjunctive  minor. 

IF  we  examine  either  of  the  forms  of  conditional  syllogism 
above  given,  we  shall  see  that  the  validity  of  the  argument 
does  not  depend  upon  any  considerations  which  have  reference 
to  the  terms  A,  B,  C,  D,  considered  as  the  representatives 
of  individuals  or  6f  classes.  We  may,  in  fact,  represent  the 
Propositions  A  is  B,  C  is  D,  by  the  arbitrary  symbols  X  and  Y 
respectively,  and  express  our  syllogisms  in  such  forms  as  the 
following : 

If  X  is  true,  then  Y  is  true, 

But  X  is  true, therefore  Y  is  true. 

Thus,  what  we  have  to  consider  is  not  objects  and  classes 
of  objects,  but  the  truths  of  Propositions,  namely,  of  those 


OF    HYPOTHKTICALS, 


49 


elementary  Propositions  which  are  embodied  in  the  terms  of 
our  hypothetical  premises. 

To  the  symbols  X,  Y,  Z,  representative  of  Propositions,  we 
may  appropriate  the  elective  symbols  x,  y,  z,  in  the  following 

sense. 

The  hypothetical  Universe,  1,  shall  comprehend  all  conceiv 
able  cases  and  conjunctures  of  circumstances. 

The  elective  symbol  x  attached  to  any  subject  expressive  of 
such  cases  shall  select  those  cases  in  which  the  Proposition  X 
is  true,  and  similarly  for  Y  and  Z. 

If  we  confine  ourselves  to  the  contemplation  of  a  given  pro 
position  X,  and  hold  in  abeyance  every  other  consideration, 
then  two  cases  only  are  conceivable,  viz.  first  that  the  given 
Proposition  is  true,  and  secondly  that  it  is  false*  As  these 
cases  together  make  up  the  Universe  of  the  Proposition,  and 
as  the  former  is  determined  by  the  elective  symbol  x,  the  latter 
is  determined  by  the  symbol  1  -  x. 

But  if  other  considerations  are  admitted,  each  of  these  cases 
will  be  resolvable  into  others,  individually  less  extensive,  the 

*  It  was  upon  the  obvious  principle  that  a  Proposition  is  either  true  or  false, 
that  the  Stoics,  applying  it  to  assertions  respecting  future  events,  endeavoured 
to  establish  the  doctrine  of  Fate.  It  has  been  replied  to  their  argument,  that 
involves  "  an  abuse  of  the  word  true,  the  precise  meaning  of  which  is  id  quod 
res  est.  An  assertion  respecting  the  future  is  neither  true  nor  false."— Copleston 
on  Necessity  and  Predestination,  p.  36.  Were  the  Stoic  axiom,  however,  pre 
sented  under  the  form,  It  is  either  certain  that  a  given  event  will  take  place, 
or  certain  that  it  will  not ;  the  above  reply  would  fail  to  meet  the  difficulty. 
The  proper  answer  would  be,  that  no  merely  verbal  definition  can  settle  the 
question,  what  is  the  actual  course  and  constitution  of  Nature.  When  we 
affirm  that  it  is  either  certain  that  an  event  will  take  place,  or  certain  that 
it  will  not  take  place,  we  tacitly  assume  that  the  order  of  events  is  necessary, 
that  the  Future  is  but  an  evolution  of  the  Present ;  so  that  the  state  of  things 
which  is,  completely  determines  that  which  shall  be.  But  this  (at  least  as  re 
spects  the  conduct  of  moral  agents)  is  the  very  question  at  issue.  Exhibited 
under  its  proper  form,  the  Stoic  reasoning  does  not  involve  an  abuse  of  terms, 
but  a  petitio  principii. 

It  should  be  added,  that  enlightened  advocates  of  the  doctrine  of  Necessity 
in  the  present  day,  viewing  the  end  as  appointed  only  in  and  through  the 
means,  justly  repudiate  those  practical  01  consequences  which  are  the  reproa 
of  Fatalism. 


50  ON    HYPOTHETICALS. 

number  of  which  will  depend  upon  the  number  of  foreign  con 
siderations  admitted.  Thus  if  we  associate  the  Propositions  X 
and  Y,  the  total  number  of  conceivable  cases  will  be  found  as 
exhibited  in  the  following  scheme. 

Cases.  Elective  expressions. 

1st  X  true,  Y  true xy 

2nd  X  true,  Y  false x  (1  -  y) 

3rd  X  false,  Y  true (I  -  z)  y 

4th  X  false,  Y  false (1 -*)(!- y)     (24)- 

If  we  add  the  elective  expressions  for  the  two  first  of  the 
above  cases  the  sum  is  x,  which  is  the  elective  symbol  appro 
priate  to  the  more  general  case  of  X  being  true  independently 
of  any  consideration  of  Y ;  and  if  we  add  the  elective  expres 
sions  in  the  two  last  cases  together,  the  result  is  1  -  xy  which 
is  the  elective  expression  appropriate  to  the  more  general  case 
of  X  being  false. 

Thus  the  extent  of  the  hypothetical  Universe  does  not  at 
all  depend  upon  the  number  of  circumstances  which  are  taken 
into  account.  And  it  is  to  be  noted  that  however  few  or  many 
those  circumstances  may  be,  the  sum  of  the  elective  expressions 
representing  every  conceivable  case  will  be  unity.  Thus  let 
us  consider  the  three  Propositions,  X,  It  rains,  Y,  It  hails, 
Z,  It  freezes.  The  possible  cases  are  the  following  : 

Cases.  Elective  expressions. 

1st  It  rains,  hails,  and  freezes,  xyz 

2nd  It  rains  and  hails,  but  does  not  freeze  xy  (1  -  z) 

3rd  It  rains  and  freezes,  but  does  not  hail  xz  (1  -  y) 

4th  It  freezes  and  hails,  but  does  not  rain  yz  (1  -  x) 

5th  It  rains,  but  neither  hails  nor  freezes  x  (1  -  y)  (1  -  z) 

6th  It  hails,  but  neither  rains  nor  freezes  y  (1  -  x)  (1  -  z) 

7th  It  freezes,  but  neither  hails  nor  rains  z  (I  -  x)(l  -  y) 

8th  It  neither  rains,  hails,  nor  freezes        (1  -  x)(l  -  y)  (1  -  z) 

1  =  sum 


OF     HYPOTHET1CALS. 


51 


Expression  of  Hypothetical  Propositions. 

To  express  that  a  given  Proposition  X  is  true. 

The  symbol  1  -  x  selects  those  cases  in  which  the  Proposi 
tion  X  is  false.  But  if  the  Proposition  is  true,  there  are  no 
such  cases  in  its  hypothetical  Universe,  therefore 

1  -  x  =  0, 
or  x  =  1,     (25). 

To  express  that  a  given  Proposition  X  is  false. 

The  elective  symbol  x  selects  all  those  cases  in  which  the 
Proposition  is  true,  and  therefore  if  the  Proposition  is  false, 

x  =  0,     (26). 

And  in  every  case,  having  determined  the  elective  expression 
appropriate  to  a  given  Proposition,  we  assert  the  truth  of  that 
Proposition  by  equating  the  elective  expression  to  unity,  and 
its  falsehood  by  equating  the  same  expression  to  0. 

To  express  that  two  Propositions,  X  and  Y,  are  simulta 
neously  true. 

The  elective  symbol  appropriate  to  this  case  is  xy,  therefore 

the  equation  sought  is 

xy  =  1,     (27). 

To  express  that  two  Propositions,  X  and  Y,  are  simultaneously 
false. 

The  condition  will  obviously  be 

(!-*)(!  -y)=  *> 
or  x  +  y  -  xy  =  0,     (28). 

To  express  that  either  the  Proposition  X  is  true,  or  the 
Proposition  Y  is  true. 

To  assert  that  either  one  or  the  other  of  two  Propositions 
is  true,  is  to  assert  that  it  is  not  true,  that  they  are  both  false. 
Now  the  elective  expression  appropriate  to  their  both  being 
false  is  (1  -  x}  (1  -  y),  therefore  the  equation  required  is 

(1  -*)(!- sO=0, 
or  x  +  y  -  xy  =•  1,    (29). 


OF    HYPOTHETICALS. 

And,  by  indirect  considerations  of  this  kind,  may  every  dis 
junctive  Proposition,  however  numerous  its  members,  be  ex 
pressed.  But  the  following  general  Rule  will  usually  be 
preferable. 

RULE.  Consider  what  are  those  distinct  and  mutually  exclusive 
cases  of  which  it  is  implied  in  the  statement  of  the  given  Propo 
sition,  that  some  one  of  them  is  true,  and  equate  the  sum  of  their 
elective  expressions  to  unity.  This  will  give  the  equation  of  the 
given  Proposition. 

For  the  sum  of  the  elective  expressions  for  all  distinct  con 
ceivable  cases  will  be  unity.  Now  all  these  cases  being  mutually 
exclusive,  and  it  being  asserted  in  the  given  Proposition  that 
some  one  case  out  of  a  given  set  of  them  is  true,  it  follows  that 
all  which  are  not  included  in  that  set  are  false,  and  that  their 
elective  expressions  are  severally  equal  to  0.  Hence  the  sum 
of  the  elective  expressions  for  the  remaining  cases,  viz.  those 
included  in  the  given  set,  will  be  unity.  Some  one  of  those 
cases  will  therefore  be  true,  and  as  they  are  mutually  exclusive, 
it  is  impossible  that  more  than  one  should  be  true.  Whence 
the  Rule  in  question. 

And  in  the  application  of  this  Rule  it  is  to  be  observed,  that 
if  the  cases  contemplated  in  the  given  disjunctive  Proposition 
are  not  mutually  exclusive,  they  must  be  resolved  into,  an  equi 
valent  series  of  cases  which  are  mutually  exclusive. 

Thus,  if  we  take  the  Proposition  of  the  preceding  example, 
viz.  Either  X  is  true,  or  Y  is  true,  and  assume  that  the  two 
members  of  this  Proposition  are  not  exclusive,  insomuch  that 
in  the  enumeration  of  possible  cases,  we  must  reckon  that  of 
the  Propositions  X  and  Y  being  both  true,  then  the  mutually 
exclusive  cases  which  fill  up  the  Universe  of  the  Proposition, 
with  their  elective  expressions,  are 

1st,    X  true  and  Y  false,  x  (I  -  y), 

2nd,  Y  true  and  X  false,  y(\  -  x\ 

3rd,   X  true  and  Y  true,  xy, 


OF    HYPOTHETIC  A  LS. 

and  the  sum  of  these  elective  expressions  equated  to  unity  gives 
x  +  y  -xy  =  1.     (30), 

as  before*  But  if  we  suppose  the  members  of  the  disjunctive 
Proposition  to  be  exclusive,  then  the  only  cases  to  be  con 
sidered  are 

1st,    X  true,  Y  false,  x  (1  -  y), 

2nd,  Y  true,  X  false,  y  (1  -  x\ 

and  the  sum  of  these  elective  expressions  equated  to  0,  gives 
x-  Ixy  +  y  =  1,     (31). 

The  subjoined  examples  will  further  illustrate  this  method. 
To  express  the  Proposition,  Either  X  is  not  true,  or  Y  is  not 
true,  the  members  being  exclusive. 

The  mutually  exclusive  cases  are 

1st,    X  not  true,  Y  true,  y  (1  -  #), 

2nd,  Y  not  true,  X  true,  x  (1  -  y), 

and  the  sum  of  these  equated  to  unity  gives 
x  -  2xy  +  y  =  1,      (32), 

which  is  the  same  as  (31),  and  in  fact  the  Propositions  which 
they  represent  are  equivalent. 

To  express  the  Proposition,  Either  X  is  not  true,  or  Y  is  not 
true,  the  members  not  being  exclusive. 

To  the  cases  contemplated  in  the  last  Example,  we  must  add 
the  following,  viz. 

X  not  true,  Y  not  true,          (1  -  x)  (1  -  y). 
The  sum  of  the  elective  expressions  gives 

#  (i  -  y)  +  y  0  -  *)  +  0  -  *)  (!  -  y)  =  ^ 

or     xy  -  0,     (33). 

To  express  the  disjunctive  Proposition,  Either  X  is  true,  or 
Y  is  true,  or  Z  is  true,  the  members  being  exclusive. 

E  2 


OF    HYPOTHETIC  A  LS. 

Here  the  mutually  exclusive  cases  are 

1st,    X  true,  Y  false,  Z  false,  x(\  -  y)  (1  -  2), 

2nd,  Y  true,  Z  false,   X  false,  y  (1  -  z)  (1  -  x), 

3rd,   Z  true,    X  false,  Y  false,  *  (1  -  a)  (1  -  y), 

and  the  sum  of  the  elective  expressions  equated  to  1,  gives, 
upon  reduction, 

x  +  y  +  z  -  2  (xy  +  yz  +  zz)  4  Say*  =  1,     (34). 

The  expression  of  the  same  Proposition,  when  the  members 
are  in  no  sense  exclusive,  will  be 

(1  -  x)  (1  -  y)  (1  -  z)  =  0,     (35). 

And  it  is  easy  to  see  that  our  method  will  apply  to  the 
expression  of  any  similar  Proposition,  whose  members  are 
subject  to  any  specified  amount  and  character  of  exclusion. 

To  express  the  conditional  Proposition,  If  X  is  true,  Y 
is  true. 

Here  it  is  implied  that  all  the  cases  of  X  being  true,  are 
cases  of  Y  being  true.  The  former  cases  being  determined 
by  the  elective  symbol  x,  and  the  latter  by  y,  we  have,  in 
virtue  of  (4), 

*(l-y)=0,     (36). 

To  express  the  conditional  Proposition,  If  X  be  true,  Y  is 
not  true. 

The  equation  is  obviously 

*y-0,     (37); 

this  is  equivalent  to  (33),  and  in  fact  the  disjunctive  Proposition, 
Either  X  is  not  true,  or  Y  is  not  true,  and  the  conditional 
Proposition,  If  X  is  true,  Y  is  not  true,  are  equivalent. 

To  express  that  If  X  is  not  true,  Y  is  not  true. 
In  (36)  write  1  -  x  for  x,  and  I  -  y  for  y,  we  have 

(i  -  *)  y  -  o. 


OF    HYPOTHETICALS. 


55 


The  resuhs  which  we  have  obtained  admit  of  verification 
in  many  different  ways.  Let  it  suffice  to  take  for  more  par 
ticular  examination  the  equation 

x-2xy  +  y=l,     (38), 

which  expresses  the  conditional  Proposition,  Either  X  is  true, 
or  Y  is  true,  the  members  being  in  this  case  exclusive. 

First,  let  the  Proposition  X  be  true,  then  z=\,  and  sub 
stituting,  we  have 

1  -  2y  +  y  =  1,        /.  -  y  =  0,    or   y  =  0, 
which  implies  that  Y  is  not  true. 

Secondly,  let  X  be  not  true,  then  x  =  0,  and  the  equation 
gives  y  =  i9  (39), 

which  implies  that  Y  is  true.     In  like  manner  we  may  proceed 
with  the  assumptions  that  Y  is  true,  or  that  Y  is  false. 

Again,  in  virtue  of  the  property  x'  =  x,  y*  =  y,  we  may  write 
the  equation  in  the  form 

x1  -  Ixy  +  y*  =  1, 
and  extracting  the  square  root,  we  have 

x  -  y  =  ±  1,    (40), 

and  this  represents  the  actual  case;   for,  as  when  X  is  true 
or  false,  Y  is  respectively  false  or  true,  we  have 

x  =  1  or  0, 
y  =  0  or   1, 
/.  x  -  y  =»  1  or  -  1. 
There  will  be  no  difficulty  in  the  analysis  of  other  cases. 

Examples  of  Hypothetical  Syllogism. 

The  treatment  of  every  form  of  hypothetical  Syllogism  will 
consist  in  forming  the  equations  of  the  premises,  and  eliminating 
the  symbol  or  symbols  which  are  found  in  more  than  one  of 
them.  The  result  will  express  the  conclusion. 


56 


OF    HYPOTHETICALS. 


1st.  Disjunctive  Syllogism. 

Either  X  is  true,  or  Y  is  true  (exclusive),  x  +  y  -  2  xy  =  1 
But  X  is  true,  x  -  1 

Therefore  Y  is  not  true,      .  /.  y  =  0 

Either  X  is  true,  or  Y  is  true  (not  exclusive),        x  +  y  -  xy  =  1 
But  X  is  not  true,  x  =  0 

Therefore  Y  is  true,  .*.  y  =  1 

2nd.  Constructive  Conditional  Syllogism. 

If  X  is  true,  Y  is  true,  x  (1  -  y)  =  0 

But  X  is  true,  x  =  I 

Therefore  Y  is  true,  .•.  1  -  y  =  0  or  y  =  1. 

3rd.  Destructive  Conditional  Syllogism. 

If  X  is  true,  Y  is  true,  x  (I  -  y)  =  0 

But  Y  is  not  true,  y  =  0 

Therefore  X  is  not  true,  .-.  x  =  0 

4th.  Simple  Constructive  Dilemma,  the  minor  premiss  ex 
clusive. 

If  X  is  true,  Y  is  true,  x  (1  -  y)  =  0,     (41), 

If  Z  is  true,  Y  is  true,  z  (1  -  y)  =  0,     (42), 

But  Either  X  is  true,  or  Z  is  true,      x-\-z  -2xz  =  1,     (43). 

From  the  equations  (41),  (42),  (43),  we  have  to  eliminate 
x  and  z.     In  whatever  way  we  effect  this,  the  result  is 

y-ii 

whence  it  appears  that  the  Proposition  Y  is  true. 

5th.  Complex  Constructive  Dilemma,  the  minor  premiss  not 
exclusive. 

If  X  is  true,  Y  is  true,  x  (l  -  y)  =  0, 

If  "W  is  true,  Z  is  true,  w  (1  -  z)  =  0, 

Either  X  is  true,  or  W  is  true,  x  +  w  -  xw  =  1. 

From  these  equations,  eliminating  x,  we  have 
y  +  z  -  yz  =  1, 


OF    HYPOTHETICALS.  57 

which  expresses  the  Conclusion,  Either  Y  is  true,  or  Z  is  true, 
the  members  being  non-exclusive. 

6th.  Complex  Destructive  Dilemma,  the  minor  premiss  ex 
clusive. 

If  X  is  true,  Y  is  true,  x(\  -  y)  =  0 

If  W  is  true,  Z  is  true,  w  (1  -  2)  =  0 

Either  Y  is  not  true,  or  Z  is  not  true,  y  +  z  -  2yz  =  1 . 

From  these  equations  we  must  eliminate  y  arid  z.  The 
result  is  xw  =  Qj 

which  expresses  the  Conclusion,  Either  X  is  not  true,  or  Y  is 
not  true,  the  members  not  being  exclusive. 

7th.  Complex  Destructive  Dilemma,  the  minor  premiss  not 
exclusive. 

If  X  is  true,  Y  is  true,  x(\  -  y}  =  0 

If  W  is  true,  Z  is  true,  10  ( 1  -  z)  =  0 

Either  Y  is  not  true,  or  Z  is  not  true,  yz  =  0. 

On  elimination  of  y  and  z,  we  have 

xw  -  0, 
which  indicates  the  same  Conclusion  as  the  previous  example. . 

It  appears  from  these  and  similar  cases,  that  whether  the 
members  of  the  minor  premiss  of  a  Dilemma  are  exclusive 
or  not,  the  members  of  the  (disjunctive)  Conclusion  are  never 
exclusive.  This  fact  has  perhaps  escaped  the  notice  of  logicians. 

The  above  are  the  principal  forms  of  hypothetical  Syllogism 
which  logicians  have  recognised.  It  would  be  easy,  however, 
to  extend  the  list,  especially  by  the  blending  of  the  disjunctive 
and  the  conditional  character  in  the  same  Proposition,  of  which 
the  following  is  an  example. 

If  X  is  true,  then  either  Y  is  true,  or  Z  is  true, 

x(\-y-z  +  yz)=Q 

But  Y  is  not  true,  y  =  o 

Therefore  If  X  is  true,  Z  is  true,  /.  x(\  -  z)  =  0. 


58 


OF    HYPOTHETICALS. 


That  which  logicians  term  a  Causal  Proposition  is  properly 
a  conditional  Syllogism,  the  major  premiss  of  which  is  sup 
pressed. 

The  assertion  that  the  Proposition  X  is  true,  because  the 
Proposition  Y  is  true,  is  equivalent  to  the  assertion, 

The  Proposition  Y  is  true, 
Therefore  the  Proposition  X  is  true; 

and  these  are  the  minor  premiss  and  conclusion  of  the  con 
ditional  Syllogism, 

If  Y  is  true,  X  is  true, 

But  Y  is  true, 

Therefore  X  is  true. 

And  thus  causal  Propositions  are  seen  to  be  included  in  the 
applications  of  our  general  method. 

Note,  that  there  is  a  family  of  disjunctive  and  conditional 
Propositions,  which  do  not,  of  right,  belong  to  the  class  con 
sidered  in  this  Chapter.  Such  are  those  in  which  the  force 
of  the  disjunctive  or  conditional  particle  is  expended  upon  the 
predicate  of  the  Proposition,  as  if,  speaking  of  the  inhabitants 
of  a  particular  island,  we  should  say,  that  they  are  all  either 
Europeans  or  Asiatics;  meaning,  that  it  is  true  of  each  indi 
vidual,  that  he  is  either  a  European  or  an  Asiatic.  If  we 
appropriate  the  elective  symbol  x  to  the  inhabitants,  y  to 
Europeans,  and  z  to  Asiatics,  then  the  equation  of  the  above 
Proposition  is 

x  =  xy  +  xz,    or   z(l-y-z)=0,     (a); 

to  which  we  might  add  the  condition  yz  =  0,  since  no  Europeans 
are  Asiatics.  The  nature  of  the  symbols  x,  y,  z,  indicates  that 
the  Proposition  belongs  to  those  which  we  have  before  de 
signated  as  Categorical.  Very  different  from  the  above  is  the 
Proposition,  Either  all  the  inhabitants  are  Europeans,  or  they 
are  all  Asiatics.  Here  the  disjunctive  particle  separates  Pro 
positions.  The  case  is  that  contemplated  in  (31)  of  the  pre 
sent  Chapter;  and  the  symbols  by  which  it  is  expressed, 


OF    HYPOTHETICALS.  59 

although  subject  to  the  same  laws  as  those  of  (a),  have  a  totally 
different  interpretation.* 

The  distinction  is  real  and  important.  Every  Proposition 
which  language  can  express  may  be  represented  by  elective 
symbols,  and  the  laws  of  combination  of  those  symbols  are  in 
all  cases  the  same ;  but  in  one  class  of  instances  the  symbols 
have  reference  to  collections  of  objects,  in  the  other,  to  the 
truths  of  constituent  Propositions. 

*  Some  writers,  among  whom  is  Dr.  Latham  (First  Outlines),  regard  it  as 
the  exclusive  office  of  a  conjunction  to  connect  Propositions,  not  words.  In  this 
view  I  am  not  able  to  agree.  The  Proposition,  Every  animal  is  either  rational 
or  irrational,  cannot  be  resolved  into,  Either  every  animal  is  rational,  or  every 
animal  is  irrational.  The  former  belongs  to  pure  categoricals,  the  latter  to 
hypotheticals.  In  singular  Propositions,  such  conversions  would  seem  to  be 
allowable.  This  animal  is  either  rational  t>r  irrational,  is  equivalent  to,  Either 
this  animal  is  rational,  or  it  is  irrational.  This  peculiarity  of  singular  Pro 
positions  would  almost  justify  our  ranking  them,  though  truly  universals,  in 
a  separate  class,  as  Ramus  and  his  followers  did. 


PROPERTIES    OF   ELECTIVE   FUNCTIONS. 


SINCE  elective  symbols  combine  according  to  the  laws  of 
quantity,  we  may,  by  Maclaurin's  theorem,  expand  a  given 
function  0  (x),  in  ascending  powers  of  x,  known  cases  of  failure 
excepted.  Thus  we  have 

0(*)=<K°)  +  0'(0)*  +  ^*2  +  &c,     (44). 
Now  £  =  z,  a?  =  x,  &c.,  whence 

0  W  =  0(0)  +  ^{0'(0)  +  ^r~-)  +  &c.},     (45). 

i>« 

Now  if  in  (44)  we  make  x  =  1,  we  have 

0(l)  =  0(0)  +  0'(0)+^)  +  &c., 
whence 


Substitute  this  value  for  the  coefficient  of  x  in  the  second 
member  of  (45),  and  we  have* 

0  (x)  =  0  (0)  +  (0  (1)  -  0  (0)}  x,     (46), 

*  Although  this  and  the  following  theorems  have  only  been  proved  for  those 
forms  of  functions  which  are  expansible  by  Maclaurin's  theorem,  they  may  be 
regarded  as  true  for  all  forms  whatever  ;  this  will  appear  from  the  applications. 
The  reason  seems  to  be  that,  as  it  is  only  through  the  one  form  of  expansion 
that  elective  functions  become  interpretable,  no  conflicting  interpretation  is 
possible. 

The  development  of  <#>  (x)  may  also  be  determined  thus.  By  the  known  for 
mula  for  expansion  in  factorials, 


PROPERTIES    OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS.  (U 

which  we  shall  also  employ  under  the  form 

£  (*)  =£•(!)*+  0(0)  (1-*),     (47). 

Every  function  of  x,  in  which  integer  powers  of  that  symbol 
are  alone  involved,  is  by  this  theorem  reducible  to  the  first 
order.  The  quantities  $  (0),  0  (1),  we  shall  call  the  moduli 
of  the  function  <f>(x).  They  are  of  great  importance  in  the 
theory  of  elective  functions,  as  will  appear  from  the  succeeding 
Propositions. 

PROP.  1.  Any  two  functions  </>  (x),  $  (x),  are  equivalent, 
whose  corresponding  moduli  are  equal. 

This  is  a  plain  consequence  of  the  last  Proposition.   For  since 
</>  (x)  =  </>  (0)  +  {</>  (1)  -  </>  (0)}  x, 


it  is  evident  that  if  <£  (0)  =  ^  (0),  0  (1)  =  ^  (1),  the  two 
expansions  will  be  equivalent,  and  therefore  the  functions  which 
they  represent  will  be  equivalent  also. 

The  converse  of  this  Proposition  is  equally  true,  viz. 

If  two  functions  are  equivalent,  their  corresponding  moduli 
are  equal. 

Among  the  most  important  applications  of  the  above  theorem, 
we  may  notice  the  following. 

Suppose  it  required  to  determine  for  what  forms  of  the 
function  <£  (x),  the  following  equation  is  satisfied,  viz. 

{4-  (*)}"  -  <£  O). 

Now  x  being  an  elective  symbol,  x  (x  -  1)  =  0,  so  that  all  the  terms  after  the 
second,  vanish.     Also  A0  (0)  =  0  (1)  -  </>  (0),  whence 
.<*>{•*'=  0(0)}  +  {</>(!)-</>  (0)}ar. 

The  mathematician  may  be  interested  in  the  remark,  that  this  is  not  the 
only  case  in  which  an  expansion  stops  at  the  second  term.     The  expansions  of 

the   compound  operative  functions  </>  (  —  +  x~l  }  and  0  /a?  +  [  iV*!,   ^^ 
respectively, 


See  Cambridge  Mathematical  Journal,  Vol.  iv.  p.  219. 


68  PROPERTIES    OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS. 

Here  we  at  once  obtain  for  the  expression  of  the  conditions 
in  question, 

{<#>  (0)}"  =  </>  (0).      {</>(!  )}"-*(!),     (48). 
Again,  suppose  it  required  to  determine  the  conditions  under 
which  the  following  equation  is  satisfied,  viz. 


The  general  theorem  at  once  gives 

<t>  (0)  +  (0)  =  X  (0)-     </>(!)  ^(1)  =  X(1)> 

This  result  may  also  be  proved  by  substituting  for  <j>  (#), 
^  0*0  »  X  (#)>  tne^r  expanded  forms,  and  equating  the  coefficients 
of  the  resulting  equation  properly  reduced. 

All  the  above  theorems  may  be  extended  to  functions  of  more 
than  one  symbol.  For,  as  different  elective  symbols  combine 
with  each  other  according  to  the  same  laws  as  symbols  of  quan 
tity,  we  can  first  expand  a  given  function  with  reference  to  any 
particular  symbol  which  it  contains,  and  then  expand  the  result 
with  reference  to  any  other  symbol,  and  so  on  in  succession,  the 
order  of  the  expansions  being  quite  indifferent. 

Thus  the  given  function  being  </>  (xy)  we  have 

<t>  (xy)  =  <t>  (xO)  +  {</>  (si)  -  <£  (*0)}  y, 

and  expanding  the  coefficients  with  reference  to  x,  and  reducing 
</>  (ay)  =  $  (00)  4  {<£  (10)  -  </>  (00)}  x  +  {</>  (01)  -  <£  (00)}y 

+  {<f>  (1  1)  -  <t>  (10)  -  <f>  (01)  +  4>  (00)}  xy,      (50), 
to  which  we  may  give  the  elegant  symmetrical  form 


y,     (51), 

wherein  we  shall,  in  accordance  with  the  language  already 
employed,  designate  <£  (00),  <£  (01),  £  (10),  ^  (11),  as  the 
moduli  of  the  function  <f>  (xy). 

By  inspection  of  the  above  general  form,  it  will  appear  that 
any  functions  of  two  variables  are  equivalent,  whose  correspond 
ing  moduli  are  all  equal. 


PROPERTIES    OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS. 

Thus  the  conditions  upon  which  depends  tbr  satisfaction  of 
the  equation, 

are  seen  to  be 

{<*>  (oo)}-  =  <£  (oo),  {<*>  (oi)}n  =  <£  (oi),    (52)> 


And  the  conditions  upon  which  depends  the  satisfaction  of 
the  equation 


are 

0  (00)  ^  (00)  =  x  (00),  <K01)t(01)  =  X(°l)>     (53). 

<f>  (10)  i|r  (10)  -  X  00),  *  00  ^  O1)  =  X  OI). 

It  is  very  easy  to  assign  by  induction  from  (47)  and  (51),  the 
general  form  of  an  expanded  elective  function.  It  is  evident 
that  if  the  number  of  elective  symbols  is  m,  the  number  of  the 
moduli  will  be  2m,  and  that  their  separate  values  will  be  obtained 
by  interchanging  in  every  possible  way  the  values  1  and  0  in  the 
places  of  the  elective  symbols  of  the  given  function.  The  several 
terms  of  the  expansion  of  which  the  moduli  serve  as  coefficients, 
will  then  be  formed  by  writing  for  each  1  that  recurs  under  the 
functional  sign,  the  elective  symbol  x,  &c.,  which  it  represents, 
and  for  each  0  the  corresponding  1  -  x,  &c.,  and  regarding  these 
as  factors,  the  product  of  which,  multiplied  by  the  modulus  from 
which  they  are  obtained,  constitutes  a  term  of  the  expansion. 

Thus,  if  we  represent  the  moduli  of  any  elective  function 
<£  (xy  .  .  .)  by  al9  0,,  .  .  ar,  the  function  itself,  when  expanded 
and  arranged  with  reference  to  the  moduli,  will  assume  the  form 


in  which  tf^.  .tr  are  functions  of  x,  y.  .,  resolved  into  factors 
of  the  forms  xy  y,.  .  1  -  x,  1  -  y,  .  .  .  &c.  These  functions  satisfy 
individually  the  index  relations 

*,"-*i»     V  =  '2>    &c- 
and  the  further  relations, 

*=0  ..  *=°     &c- 


64  PROPERTIES    OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS. 

the  product  of  any  two  of  them  vanishing.  This  will  at  once 
be  inferred  from  inspection  of  the  particular  forms  (47)  and  (51). 
Thus  in  the  latter  we  have  for  the  values  of  tl9  t^  &c.,  the  forms 


and  it  is  evident  that  these  satisfy  the  index  relation,  and  that 
their  products  all  vanish.  We  shall  designate  tJ2.  .  as  the  con 
stituent  functions  of  <j>  (xy),  and  we  shall  define  the  peculiarity 
of  the  vanishing  of  the  binary  products,  by  saying  that  those 
functions  are  exclusive.  And  indeed  the  classes  which  they 
represent  are  mutually  exclusive. 

The  sum  of  all  the  constituents  of  an  expanded  function  is 
unity.     An  elegant  proof  of  this  Proposition  will  be  obtained 
by  expanding  1  as  a  function  of  any  proposed  elective  symbols. 
Thus  if  in  (51)  we  assume  <£  (xy)  =  1,  we  have  <f>  (1 1)  =  1, 
$(10)=1,     </>(01)=l,     <£(00)=1,     and  (51)  gives 
1  =  xy  +  x  (1  -  y)  +  (1  -  x)  y  +  (1  -  x)  (1  -  y),     (57).. 

It  is  obvious  indeed,  that  however  numerous  the  symbols 
involved,  all  the  moduli  of  unity  are  unity,  whence  the  sum 
of  the  constituents  is  unity. 

We  are  now  prepared  to  enter  upon  the  question  of  the 
general  interpretation  of  elective  equations.  For  this  purpose 
we  shall  find  the  following  Propositions  of  the  greatest  service. 

PROP.  2.  If  the  first  member  of  the  general  equation 
<£  (xy...)  =  0,  be  expanded  in  a  series  of  terms,  each  of  which 
is  of  the  form  at,  a  being  a  modulus  of  the  given  function,  then 
for  every  numerical  modulus  a  which  does  not  vanish,  we  shall 
have  the  equation  at  =  Q 

and  the  combined  interpretations  of  these  several  equations  will 
express  the  full  significance  of  the  original  equation. 

For,  representing  the  equation  under  the  form 

at\  •*'  aA  •  •  +  aJr  =0,     (58). 
-Multiplying  by  tlt  we  have,  by  (56), 
a.t.  =  0,     (59), 


PROPERTIES   OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS.  (55 

whence  if  o1  is  a  numerical  constant  which  does  not  vanish, 

f,-0, 

and  similarly  for  all  the  moduli  which  do  not  vanish.  And 
inasmuch  as  from  these  constituent  equations  we  can  form  the 
given  equation,  their  interpretations  will  together  express  its 
entire  significance. 

Thus  if  the  given  equation  were 

x  -  y  =  0,     Xs  and  Ys  are  identical,     (60), 

we  should  have  <£(11)=  °>  <£(10)=  l>  <#>  (01)  =  -  1,  ^  (00)  =  0, 
so  that  the  expansion  (51)  would  assume  the  form 

* (i  -y)  -  y  U  -  *)  -  o, 

whence,  by  the  above  theorem, 

x  (1  -  y)  =  0,  All  Xs  are  Ys, 

y  (1  -  x)  =  0,  All  Ys  are  Xs, 

results  which  are  together  equivalent  to  (60). 

It  may  happen  that  the  simultaneous  satisfaction  of  equations 
thus  deduced,  may  require  that  one  or  more  of  the  elective 
symbols  should  vanish.  This  would  only  imply  the  nonexistence 
of  a  class :  it  may  even  happen  that  it  may  lead  to  a  final 
result  of  the  form  1  =  0, 

which  would  indicate  the  nonexistence  of  the  logical  Universe. 
Such  cases  will  only  arise  when  we  attempt  to  unite  contra 
dictory  Propositions  in  a  single  equation.  The  manner  in  which 
the  difficulty  seems  to  be  evaded  in  the  result  is  characteristic. 

It  appears  from  this  Proposition,  that  the  differences  in  the 
interpretation  of  elective  functions  depend  solely  upon  the 
number  and  position  of  the  vanishing  moduli.  No  change  in 
the  value  of  a  modulus,  but  one  which  causes  it  to  vanish, 
produces  any  change  in  the  interpretation  of  the  equation  in 
which  it  is  found.  If  among  the  infinite  number  of  different 
values  which  we  are  thus  permitted  to  give  to  the  moduli  which 
do  not  vanish  in  a  proposed  equation,  any  one  value  should  be 


66  PROPERTIES    OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS. 

preferred,  it  is  unity,  for  when  the  moduli  of  a  function  are  all 
either  0  or  1  ,  the  function  itself  satisfies  the  condition 

{*(«y  ••)}"  =  <£Oy---V 

and  this  at  once  introduces  symmetry  into  our  Calculus,  and 
provides-  us  with  fixed  standards  for  reference. 

PROP.  3.  If  w  =  </>  (xy  .  .),  w,  x,  y,  .  .  being  elective  symbols, 
and  if  the  second  member  be  completely  expanded  and  arranged 
in  a  series  of  terms  of  the  form  at,  we  shall  be  permitted 
to  equate  separately  to  0  every  term  in  which  the  modulus  a 
does  not  satisfy  the  condition 

an  =  a, 

and  to  leave  for  the  value  of  ».»  the  sum  of  the  remaining  terms. 

As  the  nature  of  the  demonstration  of  this  Proposition  is 
quite  unaffected  by  the  number  of  the  terms  in  the  second 
member,  we  will  for  simplicity  confine  ourselves  to  the  sup 
position  of  there  being  four,  and  suppose  that  the  moduli  of  the 
two  first  only,  satisfy  the  index  law. 

We  have  then 

w  =  a^  +  afz  +  a/3  +  af^     (61), 

with  the  relations  a"  «  alt     a"  =  az, 

in  addition  to  the  two  sets  of  relations  connecting  tlf  £2,  £3,  £4, 
in  accordance  with  (55)  and  (56). 
Squaring  (61),  we  have 

w  =  ah  +  a^  +  a\t^  4  a\tit 
and  subtracting  (61)  from  this, 

«-03K  +  K2-«4K=°; 

and  it  being  an  hypothesis,  that  the  coefficients  of  these  terms 
do  not  vanish,  we  have,  by  Prop.  2, 


whence  (61)  becomes 

2  .  a^  +  a&. 

The  utility  of  this  Proposition  will  hereafter  appear. 


PROPERTIES    OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS.  67 

PROP.  4.    The  functions  £,£,.  ,tr  being  mutually  exclusive,  we 
shall  always  have 

^  («A  +  «A  •  •  +  0r*r)  =  ^  fa)  ^  +  ^  («,)  *8  -  -  +  t  00  *o       (^j, 

whatever  may  be  the  values  of  a^  .  .  ar  or  the  form  of  -\Jr. 

Let  the  function  af^  +  02#2  .  .  +  artr  be  represented  by  </>  (:ry. .  . ), 

then  the  moduli  a^a2 .  .  ar  will  be  given  by  the  expressions 

$(11..),  </>(10..);   (...)<£  (00.  .)« 
Also  ty  (a^  +  azt.z  .  .  +  a,tr)  =  ->|r  {</>  (ajy.  .)} 

=  ^  {</>  (11 .  .)}  xy.  .  +  ^r  {<#>  (10)}  a:  (1  -  y) ... 

-,  ^r  {</>  (00)}  (1  -*)(l-y)... 

=  ^r  (Ol)  ary.  .  -f  ^r(«8)  a:  (1  -  y)  ...  +  ^  (Of)  (1  -  *)  (1  -  y).,. 
=  t  («J  ^  +  ^  («,)  *,  •  •  +  f  («0  tr,     (64). 

It  would  not  be  difficult  to  extend  the  list  of  interesting 
properties,  of  which  the  above  are  examples.  But  those  which 
we  have  noticed  are  sufficient  for  our  present  requirements. 
The  following  Proposition  may  serve  as  an  illustration  of  their 
utility. 

PROP.  5.  Whatever  process  of  reasoning  we  apply  to  a  single 
given  Proposition,  the  result  will  either  be  the  same  Proposition 
or  a  limitation  of  it. 

Let  us  represent  the  equation  of  the  given  Proposition  under 
its  most  general  form, 

tf^-f  aztz..  +  artr=  0,     (65), 

resolvable  into  as  many  equations  of  the  form  t  =  0  as  there  are 
moduli  which  do  not  vanish. 

Now  the  most  general  transformation  of  this  equation  is 

^r  (ajt,  +  «A  .  .  -f  atr)  =  ^  (0),     (66), 

provided  that  we  attribute  to  i|r  a  perfectly  arbitrary  character, 
allowing  it  even  to  involve  new  elective  symbols,  having  any 
proposed  relation  to  the  original  ones. 

P 


68  PROPERTIES    OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS. 

The  development  of  (66)  gives,  by  the  last  Proposition, 
^  (<)  *,  +  ^  (O  tz  .  .  +Vr  (af)  tr  =  1r  (0). 

To  reduce  this  to  the  general  form  of  reference,  it  is  only  neces 
sary  to  observe  that  since 

^+^,.4«r-  1, 

we  may  write  for  ^  (0), 


whence,  on  substitution  and  transposition, 

{*  (a,)  -  *  (0)}  «,  H-  {^  (Oj)  -  ^  (0)}  *z  .  .  +  {t  (a,)  -  *  (0)}  *,  -  0. 

From  which  it  appears,  that  if  a  be  any  modulus  of  the 
original  equation,  the  corresponding  modulus  of  the  transformed 
equation  will  be  <\fr  (a)  -  ty  (0). 

If  a  =  0,  then  yfr  (a)  -  ^  (0)  =  i/r  (0)  -  -f  (0)  =  0,  whence 
there  are  no  new  terms  in  the  transformed  equation,  and  there 
fore  there  are  no  new  Propositions  given  by  equating  its  con 
stituent  members  to  0. 

Again,  since  ^  (a)  -  ty  (0)  may  vanish  without  a  vanishing, 
terms  may  be  wanting  in  the  transformed  equation  which  existed 
in  the  primitive.     Thus  some  of  the  constituent  truths  of  the 
original  Proposition  may  entirely  disappear  from  the  interpre 
tation  of  the  final  result. 

Lastly,  if  ^  (a)  -  ^r  (0)  do  not  vanish,  it  must  either  be 
a  numerical  constant,  or  it  must  involve  new  elective  symbols. 
In  the  former  case,  the  term  in  which  it  is  found  will  give 

*-0, 

which  is  one  of  the  constituents  of  the  original  equation  :  in  the 
latter  case  we  shall  have 

(^  (a  -  +  (0)}  t  =  0, 

in  which  t  has   a  limiting  factor.     The  interpretation   of  this 
equation,  therefore,  is  a  limitation  of  the  interpretation  of  (65). 


PROPERTIES    OF    ELECTIVE    FUNCTIONS.  69 

The  purport  of  the  last  investigation  will  be  more  apparent 
to  the  mathematician  than  to  the  logician.  As  from  any  mathe 
matical  equation  an  infinite  number  of  others  may  be  deduced, 
it  seemed  to  be  necessary  to  shew  that  when  the  original 
equation  expresses  a  logical  Proposition,  every  member  of  the 
derived  series,  even  when  obtained  by  expansion  under  a  func 
tional  sign,  admits  of  exact  and  consistent  interpretation. 


F2 


OF  THE  SOLUTION  OF  ELECTIVE  EQUATIONS. 


IN  whatever  way  an  elective  symbol,  considered  as  unknown, 
may  be  involved  in  a  proposed  equation,  it  is  possible  to  assign 
its  complete  value  in  terms  of  the  remaining  elective  symbols 
considered  as  known.  It  is  to  be  observed  of  such  equations, 
that  from  the  very  nature  of  elective  symbols,  they  are  neces 
sarily  linear,  and  that  their  solutions  have  a  very  close  analogy 
with  those  of  linear  differential  equations,  arbitrary  elective 
symbols  in  the  one,  occupying  the  place  of  arbitrary  constants 
in  the  other.  The  method  of  solution  we  shall  in  the  first  place 
illustrate  by  particular  examples,  and,  afterwards,  apply  to  the 
investigation  of  general  theorems. 

Given  (1  -  x)  y  =  0,  (All  Ys  are  Xs),  to  determine  y  in 
terms  of  x. 

As  y  is  a  function  of  x,  we  may  assume  y  =  vx  +  v'  (1  -  x\ 
(such  being  the  expression  of  an  arbitrary  function  of  x),  the 
moduli  v  and  v  remaining  to  be  determined.  We  have  then 

(1  -x)  [vx  +  v'(l  -#)}  =  0, 
or,  on  actual  multiplication, 

v  (1  -  x)  =  0: 

that  this  may  be  generally  true,  without  imposing  any  restriction 
upon  X,  we  must  assume  v  =  0,  and  there  being  no  condition  to 
limit  vy  we  have 

y  =  vx,     (67). 

This  is  the  complete  solution  of  the  equation.  The  condition 
that  y  is  an  elective  symbol  requires  that  v  should  be  an  elective 


OF    THE    SOLUTION    OF    ELECTIVE    EQUATIONS. 


71 


symbol  also  (since  it  must  satisfy  the  index  law),  its  interpre 
tation  in  other  respects  being  arbitrary. 

Similarly  the  solution  of  the  equation,  xy  =  0,  is 

y  =  v  (1  -  *),     (68). 

Given  (1  -  x)  zy  =  0,  (All  Ys  which  are  Zs  are  Xs),  to  deter 
mine  y. 

As  y  is  a  function  of  x  and  2,  we  may  assume 

y  =  v  (i  _  x)  (i  _  *)  +  t,'  (l  -  X)  z  +  v"x  (1  -  *)  +  v'"zx. 

And  substituting,  we  get 

v  (1  -  x)z  =  0, 

whence  v  =  0.     The  complete  solution  is  therefore 

y  =  v  (1  -  x)  (1  -  z)  +  »"#  0  -  *)  +  t?'"a*,     (69), 

t/,  t>",  t)'",  being  arbitrary  elective  symbols,  and  the  rigorous 
interpretation  of  this  result  is,  that  Every  Y  is  either  a  not-X 
and  not-Z,  or  an  X  and  not-Z,  or  an  X  and  Z. 

It  is  deserving  of  note  that  the  above  equation  may,  in  con 
sequence  of  its  linear  form,  be  solved  by  adding  the  two 
particular  solutions  with  reference  to  x  and  z ;  and  replacing 
the  arbitrary  constants  which  each  involves  by  an  arbitrary 
function  of  the  other  symbol,  the  result  is 

y -**(*)  + (!-*)*(*)»     (70). 

To  shew  that  this  solution  is  equivalent  to  the  other,  it  is 
only  necessary  to  substitute  for  the  arbitrary  functions  $  (z), 
$  (x),  their  equivalents 

wz  +  w'  (1  -  z)  and  w"x  +  w"  (1  -  #), 
we  get     y  =  wxz  +  (w  +  w")  x(\  -  z)  +  w"'  (1  -  z)  (1  -  z). 

In  consequence  of  the  perfectly  arbitrary  character  of  w'  and 
w",  we  may  replace  their  sum  by  a  single  symbol  w,  whence 

y  =  wxz  -i-  w'x  (1  -  z)  +  w"  (1  -  x)  (1  -  z), 
which  agrees  with  (69). 


7£  OF    THE    SOLUTION    OF    ELECTIVE    EQUATIONS. 

The  solution  of  the  equation  wx  (1  -  y]z  =  0,  expressed  by 
arbitrary  functions,  is 

z  =  (1  -  w)  <f>  (xy)  +  (1  -  x)  $  (toy)  +  yx  (wx\  (71). 
These  instances  may  serve  to  shew  the  analogy  which  exists 
between  the  solutions  of  elective  equations  and  those  of  the 
corresponding  order  of  linear  differential  equations.  Thus  the 
expression  of  the  integral  of  a  partial  differential  equation, 
either  by  arbitrary  functions  or  by  a  series  with  arbitrary  coef 
ficients,  is  in  strict  analogy  with  the  case  presented  in  the  two 
last  examples.  To  pursue  this  comparison  further  would  minis 
ter  to  curiosity  rather  than  to  utility.  We  shall  prefer  to  con 
template  the  problem  of  the  solution  of  elective  equations  under 
its  most  general  aspect,  which  is  the  object  of  the  succeeding 
investigations. 

To  solve  the  general  equation  <f>  (xy)  =  0,  with  reference  to  y. 
If  we  expand  the  given  equation  with  reference  to  x  and  y, 
we  have 


y  =  0,     (72), 

the  coefficients  <f>  (00)  &c.  being  numerical  constants. 
Now  the  general  expression  of  y,  as  a  function  of  x,  is 
y  =  ttzr-f  v  (1  -  x\ 

v  and  v'  being  unknown  symbols  to  be  determined.  Substituting 
this  value  in  (72),  we  obtain  a  result  which  may  be  written  in 
the  following  form, 

[<£  (10)  +  {</>  (11)  -  4  (10)}  v]x+U>  (00)  +  {</>  (00)  -  $  (00)}  v'] 

(1  -*)=0; 

and  in  order  that  this  equation  may  be  satisfied  without  any 
way  restricting  the  generality  of  x,  we  must  have 


<£  (00)  -i-  {<£  (01)  -  (f>  (00)}  v  =  0, 


OF    THE    SOLUTION    OF    ELECTIVE    EQUATIONS.  73 


from  which  we  deduce 
wherefore 


0(10)  ,  0  (00) 

"  ' 


Had  we  expanded  the  original  equation  with  respect  to  y 
only,  we  should  have  had 

0(zO)  +  (0(*l)-0(*0)}y  =  0; 

but  it  might  have  startled  those  who  are  unaccustomed  to  the 
processes  of  Symbolical  Algebra,  had  we  from  this  equation 
deduced  0  (x  0) 


because  of  the  apparently  meaningless  character  of  the  second 
member.  Such  a  result  would  however  have  been  perfectly 
lawful,  and  the  expansion  of  the  second  member  would  have 
given  us  the  solution  above  obtained.  I  shall  in  the  following 
example  employ  this  method,  and  shall  only  remark  that  those 
to  whom  it  may  appear  doubtful,  may  verify  its  conclusions  by 
the  previous  method. 

To  solve  the  general  equation  0  (xyz)  =  0,  or  in  other  words 
to  determine  the  value  of  z  as  a  function  of  x  and  y. 

Expanding  the  given  equation  with  reference  to  z,  we  have 

0  (xyO)  +  {0  (xy\}  -  0  (xyO)}  .  z  =  0  ; 

...(74), 

and  expanding  the  second  member  as  a  function  of  x  and  y  by 
aid  of  the  general  theorem,  we  have 

<ft(no)        CTI        »QQQ)        x(l 

0(110) -0(111)    '        0(100) -0(101) 

*(qio) n_,w,     <KOO°)     (1_ 

(000)-  0(001)v  . 

(75) 


74  OF    THE    SOLUTION    OF    ELECTIVE    EQUATIONS. 

and  this  is  the  complete  solution  required.  By  the  same 
method  we  may  resolve  an  equation  involving  any  proposed 
number  of  elective  symbols. 

In  the  interpretation  of  any  general  solution  of  this  nature, 
the  following  cases  may  present  themselves. 

The  values  of  the  moduli  0(00),  (f>  (01),  &c.  being  constant, 
one  or  more  of  the  coefficients  of  the  solution  may  assume 
the  form  g  or  J.  In  the  former  case,  the  indefinite  symbol  g 
must  be  replaced  by  an  arbitrary  elective  symbol  v.  In  the 
latter  case,  the  term,  which  is  multiplied  by  a  factor  J  (or  by 
any  numerical  constant  except  1),  must  be  separately  equated 
to  0,  and  will  indicate  the  existence  of  a  subsidiary  Proposition. 
This  is  evident  from  (62). 

Ex.  Given  x  (1  -  y)=  0,  All  Xs  are  Ys,  to  determine  y  as 
a  function  of  x. 

Let  0  (xy)  =  x(l-  y),  then  0(10)  =  1,  <t>  (11)-  0,  0  (01)  =  0, 
0  (00)  =  0  ;  whence,  by  (73), 


-*  +  »(!-*),     (76), 

v  being  an  arbitrary  elective  symbol.  The  interpretation  of  this 
result  is  that  the  class  Y  consists  of  the  entire  class  X  with  an 
indefinite  remainder  of  not-Xs.  This  remainder  is  indefinite  in 
the  highest  sense,  t.  e.  it  may  vary  from  0  up  to  the  entire  class 
of  not-Xs. 

Ex.    Given  x  (\  -  z)  +  z  =y,  (the   class   Y  consists  of  the 
entire  class  Z,  with  such  not-Zs  as  are  Xs),  to  find  Z. 

Here  0  (xyz)  =  x  (1  -  z)  -  y  +  z,  whence  we  have  the  fol 
lowing  set  of  values  for  the  moduli, 

0(110)=  0,         0(111)=  0,     0(100)=  1,     0(101)=  1, 

0(010)=-!,      0(011)  =  0,     0(000)=0,     0(001)  =  1, 
and  substituting  these  in  the  general  formula  (75),  we  have 


OF    THE    SOLUTION    OF   ELECTIVE    EQUATIONS.  75 

the  infinite  coefficient  of  the  second  term  indicates  the  equation 
x  (1  -  y)  =  0,  All  Xs  are  Ys  ; 

and  the  indeterminate  coefficient  of  the  first  term  being  replaced 
by  v,  an  arbitrary  elective  symbol,  we  have 

2  =  (1  -  x]  y  +  vxy, 

the  interpretation  of  which  is,  that  the  class  Z  consists  of  all  the 
Ys  which  are  not  Xs,  and  an  indefinite  remainder  of  Ys  which 
are  Xs.  Of  course  this  indefinite  remainder  may  vanish.  The 
two  results  we  have  obtained  are  logical  inferences  (not  very 
obvious  ones)  from  the  original  Propositions,  and  they  give  us 
all  the  information  which  it  contains  respecting  the  class  Z,  and 
its  constituent  elements. 

Ex.  Given  x  -  y  (1  -  z)  +  z(\  -  y).  The  class  X  consists  of 
all  Ys  which  are  not-Zs,  and  all  Zs  which  are  not-Ys :  required 
the  class  Z. 

We  have 

0  Oy*)  -  s  -  y  (i  -  «)  -  *  (i  -  y), 

<£(110)=  0,       </>(lll)=l,     0(100)=  1,     0(101)  =  0, 
0(010)  =  -  1,    0(011)=  0,     0(000)=0,     0(001)  =  -!; 
whence,  by  substituting  in  (7  5), 

z  =  x(\-y)  +  y(\-x},     (78), 

the  interpretation  of  which  is,  the  class  Z  consists  of  all  Xs 
which  are  not  Ys,  and  of  all  Ys  which  are  not  Xs ;  an  inference 
strictly  logical. 

Ex.   Given  y  (l  -  z  (1  -  #)}  =  0,  All  Ys  are  Zs  and  not-Xs, 
Proceeding  as  before  to  form  the  moduli,  we  have,  on  sub 
stitution  in  the  general  formulae, 

z  =  \  xy  +  \x  (1  -  y)  +  y  (1  -  *)  +  g  (1  -  *)  (1  -  y), 
or  z  =  y  (1  -  x]  +  vx  (1  -  y}  +  v'  (1  -  x)  (1  --y) 

=  y(l-*)  +  (l-y)0(*),     (79), 

with  the  relation  xy  =  0  : 

from  these  it  appears  that  No  Ys  are  Xs,  and  that  the  class  Z 


76  OF    THE    SOLUTION    OF    ELECTIVE    EQUATIONS. 

consists  of  all  Ys  which  are  not  Xs,  and  of  an  indefinite  re 
mainder  of  not-Ys. 

This  method,  in  combination  with  Lagrange's  method  of 
indeterminate  multipliers,  may  be  very  elegantly  applied  to  the 
treatment  of  simultaneous  equations.  Our  limits  only  permit  us 
to  offer  a  single  example,  but  the  subject  is  well  deserving  of 
further  investigation. 

Given  the  equations  x  (1  -  z)  =  0,  z  (1  -  y)  =  0,  All  Xs  are 
Zs,  All  Zs  are  Ys,  to  determine  the  complete  value  of  z  with 
any  subsidiary  relations  connecting  x  and  y. 

Adding  the  second  equation  multiplied  by  an  indeterminate 
constant  A,  to  the  first,  we  have 

x  (1  -  z)  +  \z  (1  -  y)  =  0, 
whence  determining  the  moduli,  and  substituting  in  (75), 

*(i-)  +  80-*)y*   (so), 


from  which  we  derive 

z  =  xy  -f  v  (1  -  x)  y, 

with  the  subsidiary  relation 

*(1  -y)=0: 

the  former  of  these  expresses  that  the  class  Z  consists  of  all  Xs 
that  are  Ys,  with  an  indefinite  remainder  of  not-Xs  that  are  Ys  ; 
the  latter,  that  All  Xs  are  Ys,  being  in  fact  the  conclusion 
of  the  syllogism  of  which  the  two  given  Propositions  are  the 
premises. 

By  assigning  an  appropriate  meaning  to  our  symbols,  all  the 
equations  we  have  discussed  would  admit  of  interpretation  in 
hypothetical,  but  it  may  suffice  to  have  considered  them  as 
examples  of  categoricals. 

That  peculiarity  of  elective  symbols,  in  virtue  of  which  every 
elective  equation  is  reducible  to  a  system  of  equations  tf,  =  0, 
£3  =  0,  &c.,  so  constituted,  that  all  the  binary  products  £/2,  tj# 
&c.,  vanish,  represents  a  general  doctrine  in  Logic  with  re 
ference  to  the  ultimate  analysis  of  Propositions,  of  which  it 
may  be  desirable  to  offer  some  illustration. 


OF    THE    SOLUTION    OF    ELECTIVE    EQUATIONS.  77 

Any  of  these  constituents  tl9  *3,  &c.  consists  only  of  factors 
of  the  forms  x,  y,...l  -  w,  \  -  z,  Sec.  In  categoricals  it  there 
fore  represents  a  compound  class,  i.  e.  a  class  defined  by  the 
presence  of  certain  Dualities,  and  by  the  absence  of  certain 
other  qualities. 

Each  constituent  equation  ^  =  0,  &c.  expresses  a  denial  of  the 
existence  of  some  class  so  defined,  and  the  different  classes  are 
mutually  exclusive. 

Thus  all  categorical  Propositions  are  resolvable  into  a  denial  of 
the  existence  of  certain  compound  classes,  no  member  of  one  such 
class  being  a  member  of  another. 

The  Proposition,  All  Xs  are  Ys,  expressed  by  the  equation 
x  (1  -  y}  =  0,  is  resolved  into  a  denial  of  the  existence  of  a 
class  whose  members  are  Xs  and  not-Ys. 

The  Proposition  Some  Xs  are  Ys,  expressed  by  t>  =  xy,  is 
resolvable  as  follows.  On  expansion, 

v  -  xy  =  vx  (1  -  y)  +  vy  (1  -  x)  +  v  (1  -  x)  (1  -  y)  -  xy  (1  -  t>); 
' 


The  three  first  imply  that  there  is  no  class  whose  members 
belong  to  a  certain  unknown  Some,  and  are  1st,  Xs  and  not  Ys; 
2nd,  Ys  and  not  Xs;  3rd,  not-Xs  and  not-Ys.  The  fourth 
implies  that  there  is  no  class  whose  members  are  Xs  and  Ys 
without  belonging  to  this  unknown  Some. 

From  the  same  analysis  it  appears  that  all  hypothetical  Propo 
sitions  may  be  resolved  into  denials  of  the  coexistence  of  the  truth 
or  falsity  of  certain  assertions. 

Thus  the  Proposition,  If  X  is  true,  Y  is  true,  is  resolvable 
by  its  equation  x  (1  -  y)  =  0,  into  a  denial  that  the  truth  of  X 
and  the  falsity  of  Y  coexist. 

And  the  Proposition  Either  X  is  true,  or  Y  is  true,  members 
exclusive,  is  resolvable  into  a  denial,  first,  that  X  and  Y  are 
both  true  ;'  secondly,  that  X  and  Y  are  both  false. 

But  it  may  be  asked,  is  not  something  more  than  a  system  of 
negations  necessary  to  the  constitution  of  an  affirmative  Pro 
position?  is  not  a  positive  element  required?  Undoubtedly 


78  OF   THE    SOLUTION    OF    ELECTIVE   EQUATIONS. 

there  is  need  of  one;  and  this  positive  element  is  supplied 
in  categoricals  by  the  assumption  (which  may  be  regarded  as 
^  prerequisite  of  reasoning  in  such  cases)  that  there  is  a  Uni 
verse  of  conceptions,  and  that  each  individual  it  contains  either 
belongs  to  a  proposed  class  or  does  not  belong  to  it ;  in  hypo- 
theticals,  by  the  assumption  (equally  prerequisite)  that  there 
is  a  Universe  of  conceivable  cases,  and  that  any  given  Pro 
position  is  either  true  or  false.  Indeed  the  question  of  the 
existence  of  conceptions  (el  e<m)  is  preliminary  to  any  statement 
of  their  qualities  or  relations  (ri  ecrri). — Aristotle,  Anal.  Post. 
lib.  ii.  cap.  2. 

It  would  appear  from  the  above,  that  Propositions  may  be 
regarded  as  resting  at  once  upon  a  positive  and  upon  a  negative 
foundation.  Nor  is  such  a  view  either  foreign  to  the  spirit 
of  Deductive  Reasoning  or  inappropriate  to  its  Method;  the 
latter  ever  proceeding  by  limitations,  while  the  former  contem 
plates  the  particular  as  derived  from  the  general. 


Demonstration  of  the  Method  of  Indeterminate  Multipliers,  as 

applied  to  Simultaneous  Elective  Equations. 
To  avoid  needless  complexity,  it  will  be  sufficient  to  consider 
the  case  of  three  equations  involving  three  elective  symbols, 
those  equations  being  the  most  general  of  the  kind.  It  will 
be  seen  that  the  case  is  marked  by  every  feature  affecting 
the  character  of  the  demonstration,  which  would  present  itself 
in  the  discussion  of  the  more  general  problem  in  which  the 
number  of  equations  and  the  number  of  variables  are  both 
unlimited. 

Let  the  given  equations  be 

0  (xyz)  =  0,     $  (xyz)  =  0,     x  (XVZ)  =  °>     C1)- 
Multiplying  the  second  and  third  of  these  by  the  arbitrary 
constants  h  and  k,  and  adding  to  the  first,  we  have 
0  (xyz)  +  h  $  (xyz}  + 


METHOD    OF    INDETERMINATE    MULTIPLIERS.  79 

and  we  are  to  shew,  that  in  solving  this  equation  with  reference 
to  any  variable  z  by  the  general  theorem  (75),  we  shall  obtain 
not  only  the  general  value  of  z  independent  of  h  and  k,  but 
also  any  subsidiary  relations  which  may  exist  between  x  and  y 
independently  of  z. 

If  we  represent  the  general  equation  (2)   under  the  form 
F(xyz)  =  0,  its  solution  may  by  (75)  be  written  in  the  form 
x(\  -y)          y(l  -a?) 


_ 

F(l\0)  JF(IOO)  F(010)  .F(OOO) 

and  we  have  seen,  that  any  one  of  these  four  terms  is  to  be 
equated  to  0,  whose  modulus,  which  we  may  represent  by  M, 
does  not  satisfy  the  condition  M"=M,  or,  which  is  here  the 
same  thing,  whose  modulus  has  any  other  value  than  0  or  1  . 
Consider  the  modulus  (suppose  3/,)  of  the  first  term,  viz. 


and  giving  to  the  symbol  F  its   full  meaning, 


F(llQ) 
we  have 


0(110) 

It  is  evident  that  the  condition  M*  =  Ml  cannot  be  satisfied 
unless  the  right-hand  member  be  independent  of  h  and  k  ;  and 
in  order  that  this  may  be  the  case,  we  must  have  the  function 

ind      dent  of  h  and  L 


^(110)+ 
Assume  then 


*(110).+  Jty(110)  +  *x(110) 

c  being  independent  of  h  and  k  ;  we  have,  on  clearing  of  frac 


tions  and  equating  coefficients, 

$(lll)«c0(110), 
whence,  eliminating  c, 


0(110) 


80  METHOD   OF    INDETERMINATE    MULTIPLIERS. 

being  equivalent  to  the  triple  system 

)^(111)  =  (M 

0        (3); 


0(110)  - 

and  it  appears  that  if  any  one  of  these  equations  is  not  satisfied, 
the  modulus  Ml  will  not  satisfy  the  condition  M*  =  Mlt  whence 
the  first  term  of  the  value  of  z  must  be  equated  to  0,  and 
we  shall  have 

xy    v9 

a  relation  between  x  and  y  independent  of  z. 

Now  if  we  expand  in  terms  of  z  each  pair  of  the  primitive 

equations  (1),  we  shall  have 

0  GryO)  +  (0  (ayl)  -  0  (xyQ)}  z  =  0, 
tf  (syO)  -f  jtf  Cryl)  -  ^(*yO)}  z  =  0, 


and  successively  eliminating  z  between  each  pair  of  these  equa 
tions,  we  have 

0  (xyl)  $  (ayO)  -  0  (ayO)  i£  (ay  1)  =  0, 


(syl)  =  0, 

which  express  all  the  relations  between  x  and  y  that  are  formed 
by  the  elimination  of  z.  Expanding  these,  and  writing  in  full 
the  first  term,  we  have 


xO  11)}  xy  +  &c.  =  0, 


and  it  appears  from  Prop.  2,  that  if  the  coefficient  of  xy  in  any 
of  these  equations  does  not  vanish,  we  shall  have  the  equation 

xy=  0; 

but  the  coefficients  in  question  are  the  same  as  the  first  members 
of  the  system  (3),  and  the  two  sets  of  conditions  exactly  agree. 
Thus,  as  respects  the  first  term  of  the  expansion,  the  method  of 
indeterminate  coefficients  leads  to  <he  same  result  as  ordinary 
elimination  ;  and  it  is  obvious  that  from  their  similarity  of  form, 
the  same  reasoning  will  apply  to  all  the  other  terms. 


METHOD    OF    INDETERMINATE    MULTIPLIERS.  81 

Suppose,  in  the  second  place,  that  the  conditions  (3)  are  satis 
fied  so  that  Ml  is  independent  of  h  and  k.  It  will  then  indif 
ferently  assume  the  equivalent  forms 

M  1  1  1 

i-lliii)    i    ^(m)    i    xO")" 
.    0(110)         ^(110)         x(no) 

These  are  the  exact  forms  of  the  first  modulus  in  the  ex 
panded  values  of  z,  deduced  from  the  solution  of  the  three 
primitive  equations  singly.  If  this  common  value  of  Ml  is  1 
or  §  =  v,  the  term  will  be  retained  in  z ;  if  any  other  constant 
value  (except  0),  we  have  a  relation  xy  =  0,  not  given  by  elimi 
nation,  but  deducible  from  the  primitive  equations  singly,  and 
similarly  for  all  the  other  terms.  Thus  in  every  case  the  ex 
pression  of  the  subsidiary  relations  is  a  necessary  accompaniment 
of  the  process  of  solution. 

It  is  evident,  upon  consideration,  that  a  similar  proof  will 
apply  to  the  discussion  of  a  system  indefinite  as  to  the  number 
both  of  its  symbols  and  of  its  equations. 


POSTSCRIPT. 

SOME  additional  explanations  and  references  which  have 
occurred  to  me  during  the  printing  of  this  work  are  subjoined. 

The  remarks  on  the  connexion  between  Logic  and  Language, 
p.  5,  are  scarcely  sufficiently  explicit.  Both  the  one  and  the 
other  I  hold  to  depend  very  materially  upon  our  ability  to  form 
general  notions  by  the  faculty  of  abstraction.  Language  is  an 
instrument  of  Logic,  but  not  an  indispensable  instrument. 

To  the  remarks  on  Cause,  p.  1 2,  I  desire  to  add  the  following  : 
Considering  Cause  as  an  invariable  antecedent  in  Nature,  (which 
is  Brown's  view),  whether  associated  or  not  with  the  idea  of 
Power,  as  suggested  by  Sir  John  Herschel,  the  knowledge  of  its 
existence  is  a  knowledge  which  is  properly  expressed  by  the  word 
that  (TO  orl),  not  by  why  (TO  Biorl).  It  is  very  remarkable  that 
the  two  greatest  authorities  in  Logic,  modern  and  ancient,  agree 
ing  in  the  latter  interpretation,  differ  most  widely  in  its  applica 
tion  to  Mathematics.  Sir  W.  Hamilton  says  that  Mathematics 


POSTSCRIPT. 

exhibit  only  the  that  (TO  orl) :  Aristotle  says,  The  why  belongs 
to  mathematicians,  for  they  have  the  demonstrations  of  Causes. 
Anal.  Post.  lib.  i.,  cap.  xiv.  It  must  be  added  that  Aristotle's 
view  is  consistent  with  the  sense  (albeit  an  erroneous  one) 
which  in  various  parts  of  his  writings  he  virtually  assigns  to  the 
word  Cause,  viz.  an  antecedent  in  Logic,  a  sense  according  to 
which  the  premises  might  be  said  to  be  the  cause  of  the  conclu 
sion.  This  view  appears  to  me  to  give]  even  to  his  physical 
inquiries  much  of  their  peculiar  character. 

Upon  reconsideration,  I  think  that  the  view  on  p.  41,  as  to  the 
presence  or  absence  of  a  medium  of  comparison,  would  readily 
follow  from  Professor  De  Morgan's  doctrine,  and  I  therefore 
relinquish  all  claim  to  a  discovery.  The  mode  in  which  it 
appears  in  this  treatise  is,  however,  remarkable. 

I  have  seen  reason  to  change  the  opinion  expressed  in 
pp.  42,  43.  The  system  of  equations  there  given  for  the  expres 
sion  of  Propositions  in  Syllogism  is  always  preferable  to  the  one 
before  employed— first,  in  generality — secondly,  in  facility  of 
interpretation. 

In  virtue  of  the  principle,  that  a  Proposition  is  either  true  or 
false,  every  elective  symbol  employed  in  the  expression  of 
hypotheticals  admits  only  of  the  values  0  and  1,  which  are  the 
only  quantitative  forms  of  an  elective  symbol.  It  is  in  fact 
possible,  setting  out  from  the  theory  of  Probabilities  (which  is 
purely  quantitative),  to  arrive  at  a  system  of  methods  and  pro 
cesses  for  the  treatment  of  hypotheticals  exactly  similar  to  those 
which  have  been  given.  The  two  systems  of  elective  symbols 
and  of  quantity  osculate,  if  I  may  use  the  expression,  in  the, 
points  0  and  1.  It  seems  to  me  to  be  implied  by  this,  that 
unconditional  truth  (categoricals)  and  probable  truth  meet  to 
gether  in  the  constitution  of  contingent  truth;  (hypotheticals). 
The  general  doctrine  of  elective  symbols  and  all  the  more  cha 
racteristic  applications  are  quite  independent  of  any  quantitative 
origin. 

THE    END. 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY 


BC  Boole,  George 

135  The  mathematical  analysis 

B6?7  of  logic 


COMPUTATION  CENTRE 
McLENNAN  LABORATORY 
UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO